work_2236vhjjobhmzflc6q7fot2rdy ---- 1The Dance of Justice Editorial The Dance of Justice Time appears in the development of law in several capacities. One of its powers is to provide relief for courts gridlocked in contradictory claims of hierarchy. That is the topic of this editorial. A showcase is provided by the Melki saga, as it re- cently unfolded in a rich and rushed contention between the French courts and the Court of Justice of the European Union.1 Melki and Abdeli, two Algerian sans papiers in France, were arrested in 2010 pursuant to an identity check in the Belgian border area and kept for deportation. Before the court they invoked rights under the French Constitution and under the EU treaties. The constitutional question was referred to the French Cour de Cassation under a new procedure based on Article 61-1 of the Constitution and effective from 1 March 2010. Upon referral from the Conseil d’État or the Cour de Cassation, the Conseil constitutionnel is allowed to test a legislative provision’s compatibility with (French) constitutional rights and liberties. The organic (insti- tutional) legislature2 turned this procedure into a question prioritaire de constitu- tionalité to give precedence to review of a contested legislative provision against the Constitution by the Conseil constitutionnel over review against international instruments by the ordinary and administrative courts. In the words of the Conseil constitutionnel, ‘Parliament, when enacting the Institutional Act, intended to en- sure compliance with the Constitution and confirm the place of the latter at the apex of the national legal system.’3 In the Melki case, in defiance of the priority rule, the Cour de Cassation, instead of referring Melki’s question to the Conseil constitutionnel, referred the new pro- cedure itself to the Court of Justice for a review against EU law. This was 16 April 2010. Less than four weeks later, on 12 May, the Constitutional Council took advantage of another dispute to convey its view that there had been no reason for the Cassation Court to worry: the constitutional question priority procedure does 1 Marc Bossuyt and Willem Verrijdt, ‘The Full Effect of EU Law and of Constitutional Review in Belgium and France after the Melki Judgment’, 7 EuConst (2011) p. 355-391. 2 Loi organique n° 2009-1523 du 10 décembre 2009 relative à l’application de l’article 61-1 de la Constitution. 3 Decision n° 2009-595 DC of 3 December 2009, para. 14. European Constitutional Law Review, 9: 1–6, 2013 © 2013 t.m.c.Asser press and Contributors doi:10.1017/S1574019612001010 use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1574019612001010 Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:32, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/S1574019612001010 https://www.cambridge.org/core 2 Editorial EuConst 9 (2013) not deprive the administrative and ordinary courts of the power to do ‘all and everything necessary to prevent the application in the case at hand of statutory provisions impeding the full effectiveness of the norms and standards of the Eu- ropean Union.’ Nor does it take away their freedom or duty to ask for a preliminary ruling under Article 267 of the Treaty on the Functioning of the European Union.4 Two days later again the French Council of State followed suit with a similar reas- surance.5 A few weeks later again, on 22 June, the Court of Justice gave its blessing to the new French procedure under the terms proposed by the two French public law courts, albeit under one important condition. This concerns the situation in which a legislative provision whose constitutionality is contested merely trans- poses the mandatory provisions of a European Union directive. In that case, the constitutionality of the underlying directive is at stake, albeit indirectly, and the Court of Justice must have had the opportunity to rule on the validity of that directive before the Constitutional Council rules on the constitutionality of the legislative provision: ‘In the case of a national implementing law with such content, the question of whether the directive is valid takes priority, in the light of the obligation to transpose that directive.’6 The upshot of the Melki saga is that the Court of Justice conceded to a limita- tion of its supremacy dogma in favour of French constitutional law. It accepted a national procedure ‘which would prevent the national court from immediately disapplying a national legislative provision which it considers to be contrary to EU law’ (para. 53), something which it had forcefully rejected in the famous Sim- menthal decision of 1978. But another element of the saga interests us even more here. In the Melki string of rulings the temporal aspect that is the most interesting is decidedly that of succession. Of course, the Court of Justice was well aware that the Constitutional Council does not accept the primacy of Union law uncondi- tionally. Indeed, although the Council qualifies the duty of the French parliament to implement directives as a constitutional one, such implementation may not ‘run counter to a rule or principle inherent in the constitutional identity of France unless the Constituent power has agreed’ to it.7 Similarly, the Court of Justice was well aware that it was unable to prevent the referral of legislative provisions that implement mandatory provisions of a directive to the Constitutional Council for constitutional review. Therefore it claimed the right to rule first on the question of the validity or constitutionality of the directive or legislative provisions. And 4 Decision n° 2010-605 DC of 12 May 2010, paras. 14 and 15. 5 CE 14 May 2010 (Rujovic). 6 CJEU 22 June 2010, Joined Cases C188/10 and C-189/10 (Melki and Abdeli), para. 56. 7 Decision n° 2010-605 DC of 12 May 2010, para. 18. use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1574019612001010 Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:32, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/S1574019612001010 https://www.cambridge.org/core 3The Dance of Justice the Court of Justice got its way. The Constitutional Council, in its judgment of 12 May 2012, unmistakably accepted that when the Cour de cassation and the Conseil d’Etat refer a question prioritaire de constitutionnalité to the Constitutional Council, they also have to put a preliminary question to the Court of Justice if the validity of the directive is at stake. Such a preliminary question will in turn put the Court of Justice under time pressure, as the decisions of the highest referring courts and that of the Constitu- tional Council concerning a question prioritaire de constitutionnalité are subject to strict time limits: the Cour de cassation and the Conseil d’Etat have only three months to decide whether or not to refer, and the Constitutional Council has the same time span to answer the constitutional question. If the preliminary question is posed at the same time as the constitutional question, the Court of Justice con- sequently has less than three months. Between the German Bundesverfassungsgericht and the Court of Justice, a sim- ilar dance is taking shape. So far between these two competitors, a relationship had developed roughly combining intransigence as to formally contradictory claims of supremacy with actual trade-offs as to substance. This relationship, going back to the first Solange ruling, has worked well but is ultimately unsatisfactory for both law and legal doctrine, as the contradiction of supremacy claims nurtures judicial unrest. Pluralism is no solution to these shortcomings. And there are other unde- sirables. Let us look at the rule of succession that emerged between these two contend- ers for primacy. On 6 July 2010 the Bundesverfassungsgericht ruled that the Court of Justice must be able to rule on an EU ultra vires issue before the German Court itself does.8 What is happening here, apart of course from the gesture of deference, is that both sides are seeking to address their hierarchical conundrum by finding a regulated, accepted, succession of appearances, a taking of turns. There is no denying that a change is slipping in with the rule that the EU Court must first have had its say before a domestic court may judge on an alleged conflict. What change? In such a succession, the claims of the last word and of highest authority are losing ground to an underlying agreement about the order of succession. And where there is agreement, the claims of ultimate hierarchy are put into perspective.9 Incidentally, this succession of appearances might be said to be inherent in the preliminary 8 BVerG, 2 BvR 2661/06 (Honeywell). 9 More fundamentally: hierarchy is often based on agreement, as is well expressed in the French maxim: Grattez le décret et vous trouverez le pacte: scratch the (vertical) decree and you’ll find the (horizontal) deal. But the wisdom is also found in figures of thought such as social contract as the basis of authority. use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1574019612001010 Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:32, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/S1574019612001010 https://www.cambridge.org/core 4 Editorial EuConst 9 (2013) proceedings of Article 267 TFEU and is accepted on that basis by several other constitutional courts. Why is the agreement acceptable to all courts involved? As to the form and in terms of logic and primacy, strictly, the French and German Courts keep the last word, while the Court of Justice will find solace in the rule that the one who has préséance is the more important one. More substantively, the agreement institu- tionalizes the oft-praised dialogue between the courts and minimizes the chances of accidents de parcours: the Court of Justice ruling with priority on the validity of secondary Union law is able to cater for national constitutional sensitivities and, in case the Court upholds a contested Union act, the national courts ruling sub- sequently are at least fully informed of the reasons for this. So what does this mean for the law and doctrine? Succession is the way for time to proceed and produce development through a chain of events. Nature uses it, life does. And so does the law, which has put this power of time to controlled use in rules of procedure, in a way we are all familiar with. The succession of events, to return to this aspect of time, also aids the develop- ment of a rough form of the law outside of this regulated sphere, as the rulings in the Melki dance above well demonstrate. Judicial rulings are always historical events in the first place (and all law is really a specific form of history). Between the French rulings from competing instances and the ruling of an even more distant court (the Court of Justice), there is a very obvious chain. The chain is, however, not governed by procedural law, as it links up different legal orders and different systems of judicial procedure. Or is it? Are there no rules of procedure in any form, governing or guiding the succession of rulings? We would suggest taking a better look: there might be some rules there, and more might be in the making. The French constitutional procedure of the question prioritaire de constitutionnalité is obviously a legal rule governing the intercourse between distinct legal systems inside France in a temporal, proce- dural way. The Melki ruling by the CJEU (and its underlying consent) extends the reign of this rule to some extent into the EU legal order. As Arthur Dyevre dem- onstrates in his delightful piece on ‘The Melki Way’, the CJEU ‘accepted the modus vivendi offered by the Conseil d’Etat and the Constitutional Council.’10 Why is all of this so fundamentally interesting? For one thing, because in all discussion about pluralism and intercourse between legal orders, so far, the idea of bringing this intercourse (dialogue, etc.) under some incipient form of law is generally refused (it was mooted by this journal a few years ago).11 What is hap- 10 A. Dyevre, ‘The Melki Way: The Melki Case and Everything You Always Wanted to Know about French Politics (but Were Afraid to Ask)’, in M. Claes et al. (eds.), Constitutional Conversa- tions in Europe. Actors, Topics and Procedures (Cambridge, Intersentia 2012) p. 309-322. 11 ‘“The Law of Laws” – Overcoming Pluralism’, 4 EuConst (2008) p. 395-398. use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1574019612001010 Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:32, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/S1574019612001010 https://www.cambridge.org/core 5The Dance of Justice pening here is just that: the creation of procedural law, regulating a succession of steps, bridging legal orders in a normative, non-hierarchical way, on the basis of agreement. But is this law, really? Constitutional doctrine generally refuses to acknowledge a form of law between distinct legal orders, because this law would have no hier- archically supreme instance on which to draw its authority. Now that is precisely what time and succession allow: an escape from the shackles of hierarchy. Can courts of law be parties in an agreement leading to law? Let us turn to our last case in point. In the negotiations for accession of the European Union to the European Convention, the Court of Justice has intervened to secure the same sort of prior review by itself of EU rules before these come under the scrutiny of the Strasbourg Court. The Strasbourg Court has accepted this formula, and together the two courts have addressed their agreement to the negotiators following one of their periodic meetings, on 17 January 2011. It is included in the draft agreement on the accession of the EU to the ECHR of 14 October 2011 and likely to be part of the accession instruments.12 It is natural for legal scholarship to find fault with courts from different legal orders seeking a role in the legislative or treaty-making process, as is happening here, and thus bridging the gulf between systems in a sort of contractual way. But one may also appreciate it as a way to shed the shackles of system and harness the powers of time. There is no need to go back to founders of ancient Greek philosophy such as Anaximander and Heraclitus, but it may help, to see how at some point in our intellectual history, Time (and the time of succession specifically) was seen to be the ultimate court and source of law. It is a poor rudiment of this understanding when we defer to History as our ultimate court of law. In our modern understand- ing, the virtues of logic and system have in many respects imposed themselves 12 ‘In proceedings to which the European Union is co-respondent, if the Court of Justice of the European Union has not yet assessed the compatibility with the Conventionrights at issue of the provision of European Union law as under para. 2 of this Article, then sufficient time shall be afford- ed for the Court of Justice of the European Union to make such an assessment and thereafter for the parties to make observations to the Court. The European Union shall ensure that such assessment is made quickly so that the proceedings before the Court are not unduly delayed. The provisions of this paragraph shall not affect the powers of the Court’; Art. 3(6) of the Draft Agreement on the Accession of the European Union to the Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms , last visited on 10 March 2013. The non-EU member states who par- ticipate in the present negotiations opposed to the prior involvement mechanism, which is viewed as contrary to the subsidiarity principle and creating a privilege for the European Court of Justice, see Appendix III, section 3, Meeting report, Fourth Negotiating Meeting, at p. 15, , last visited on 10 March 2013. use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1574019612001010 Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:32, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/S1574019612001010 https://www.cambridge.org/core 6 Editorial EuConst 9 (2013) upon law, to the detriment of the virtues of time. That is understandable and it helps to run complex modern systems of law. But when law is entering poorly chartered waters such as that of the composite constitutional order involving the EU and its member states, we should not be so averse to the powers of Time as to shun them as more direct sources of our legal understanding and even of law. The situation may be expressed by saying that judicial instances are entering together into a scheme of time-sharing. This is, then, part of their sharing a legal development. This shared reality, also between judicial instances of different origins, is most obvious from the succession of judicial events and from procedures regu- lating such succession. Here is the wide subject now put to constitutional scholarship for it to pick up and develop further. WTE/JHR q use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1574019612001010 Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:32, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/S1574019612001010 https://www.cambridge.org/core work_24nrr2r2wbc2bifwbdebw6pfnu ---- None work_27u3q3znzfcdtlqtushn4zsdmi ---- Canterbury Christ Church University’s repository of research outputs http://create.canterbury.ac.uk Please cite this publication as follows:  Hallenberg, K. and Haddow, C. (2016) Beyond criminal justice: connecting justice and sustainability. The Law Teacher, 50 (3). pp. 352-370. ISSN 0306-9400. Link to official URL (if available): http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/03069400.2016.1262985 This version is made available in accordance with publishers’ policies. All material made available by CReaTE is protected by intellectual property law, including copyright law. Any use made of the contents should comply with the relevant law. Contact: create.library@canterbury.ac.uk Final Author Version Hallenberg, K. & Haddow, C. (2016). ‘Beyond Criminal Justice: Connecting Justice and Sustainability’. The Law Teacher. Abstract: The potential of higher education in advancing sustainability has been widely accepted and even partly realised, although a wholesale reorientation of core activities and curricula toward and embedded with sustainability is still an exception. But even big changes start small and modules that address sustainability have both strategic and symbolic value particularly in disciplines and departments where it has not previously been explicitly, or at all, addressed. This paper discusses a project which aims to introduce sustainability considerations into the criminology and criminal justice curriculum by way of a new and innovative module “Criminology for a Just Society”, developed with the support and funding from the central university sustainability initiative. The module aims to facilitate a broad and nuanced understanding of sustainability and criminology’s potential to further it, focusing on the current ecological, cultural, socio-political and economic problems and ways of addressing them. This is done through a framework of (in)justice which allows students to embed new understanding within familiar disciplinary context and language. The pedagogical approach is interdisciplinary, emphasising service learning through volunteering placements and active student engagement, and assessment which embeds critical reflection and knowledge exchange. “Criminology for a Just Society” was piloted in 2014-2015 and the paper reflects on the project, drawing from both student and staff experiences to evaluate its impact and map further developments. Introduction Awareness of the rapidly increasing environmental devastation and the resulting social and economic breakdown is widespread if often superficial. The role of the Higher Education (HE) sector in deepening the understanding is not new, although considerable momentum was gained during the United Nations’ Decade of Education for Sustainable Development 2005-2014.1 It placed particular responsibility on universities regarding research, learning, leadership and curricula development to facilitate Education for Sustainable Development (ESD) and promote its underlying values of human rights, social and economic justice, intergenerational responsibility, protection and restoration of ecosystems, respect for cultural diversity and commitment to peace2. This is particularly crucial as universities and academic knowledge become increasingly commodified.3,4 Echoing Furedi,5 Walters6 argues that the value of education is measured in market terms, not for its implicit educational value, or even social or personal empowerment. ESD represents a countermovement of sorts to this, valuing education for its transformational potential, not just for the individual but for the world at large. Barth and colleagues7 see this not just equipping people with knowledge and skills to further sustainability, but also encouraging reflection on and responsibility for decisions and behaviour of oneself and others. The current paper reflects on a project aiming to introduce sustainability considerations into the criminology and criminal justice curriculum by way of a new and innovative module “Criminology for a Just Society” (CfJS). The spark for the project was of a personal and professional nature, and the introduction discusses its pedagogical and disciplinary underpinnings as well as practical development, providing a brief overview of the module itself. ESD encompasses ideas of other values-driven/adjectival educational and curriculum movements seeking to embed human rights, citizenship education, inclusivity/diversity, and democratic/collaborative approaches8,9 and can in many ways be considered an umbrella term for all. The philosophical roots of ESD and other such values-driven movements reside in liberal education and the concept of a free university, the work of Von Humboldt and Hegel, later John Dewey and John P Miller10. The approach aligns with our personal values and view of HE as playing a role in developing not just knowledgeable and skilled individuals but aware, responsible and active 1 P. Jones, D. Selby and S. Sterling, “Introduction”, in P. Jones, D. Selby, and S. Sterling (eds), Sustainability Education: Perspectives and Practice across Higher Education. (London, Earthscan, 2010). 2 UNESCO, United Nations Decade of Education for Sustainable Development (2005-14): Draft International Implementation Scheme (Paris, UNESCO, 2004). 3 R. Walters, “Critical criminology and the intensification of the authoritarian state” in A. Barton, K. Corteen, D. Scott, and D. Whyte (eds.), Expanding the criminological imagination: Critical readings in criminology (Cullompton, Willan, 2007). 4 A. Barton, K. Corteen, J. Davies and A. Hobson, “Reading the Word and Reading the World: The Impact of a Critical Pedagogical Approach to the Teaching of Criminology in Higher Education” (2010) 21 Journal of Criminal Justice Education 24-41. 5 F. Furedi, Where Have All the Intellectuals Gone? 2nd ed. (London, Continuum, 2006). 6 Walter, supra n.3 7 M. Barth, J. Godemann, M. Rieckman, and U. Stoltenberg, (2007) “Developing key competencies for sustainable development in higher education” (2007) 8 International Journal of Sustainability in Higher Education 416-430. 8 A. Ryan, Education for sustainable development and holistic curriculum change: A review and guide (London, Higher Education Academy, 2011). See: http://efsandquality.glos.ac.uk/toolkit/AR_HEA.pdf (accessed 02 June 2015) 9 D. Tilbury, Education for Sustainable Development: An Expert Review of Processes and Learning, (Paris, UNESCO, 2011). See: http://unesdoc.unesco.org/images/0019/001914/191442e.pdf (accessed 26 Novem2016) 10 Ryan, supra n. 8 ones; the 'tree of knowledge' being of and for the good11. It also reflects Canterbury Christ Church University’s (CCCU) values of “transforming individuals, creating knowledge, enriching communities and building a sustainable future”12 and its strategic aim to embed social and environmental sustainability throughout teaching and research13. Sustainability has traditionally been understood in relation to the environment and issues of ‘green development’14. Contemporary understandings have advanced this concept to include three key spheres of sustainable development: environmental, economic and social15. While each strand is relevant to criminology and law, social sustainability with its emphasis on ethics and wellbeing has particular resonance, highlighting the broad and interdisciplinary nature of sustainability. Indeed, current research highlights how the negative effects of climate change are most experienced by lower-income and other disadvantaged groups, who often contribute least toward its causes.16 This differentiated responsibility was acknowledged at nation state level as the recent COP21 Paris Agreement17 placed obligations on developed countries to provide financial assistance to the developing states. Therefore, the different spheres should not be considered as separate, but rather viewed as interlinking aspects of sustainability which work together to create a sustainable society: “A truly sustainable society is one where wider questions of social needs and welfare, and economic opportunity are integrally related to environmental limits imposed by supporting ecosystems.”18 Additional attention has been given to the importance of implementing such measures in ways which enhance and respect diversity and individual cultures, giving birth to cultural sustainability as a fourth strand19. In spite of the range of these overarching themes, the links between sustainability and other disciplines are often overlooked. Specific theoretical approaches within criminology illustrate clear overlaps with the sustainable development agenda. Building on a longstanding tradition of critical social research, critical criminology seeks to highlight aspects of crime and victimisation generally neglected within society, championing the ‘view from below’, giving voice to the voiceless and enabling grassroots change20. In parallel, the critical legal studies and critical jurisprudence approaches have continued to draw attention to the intersections of political and economic interests 11 D. Maskell and I. Robinson, The New idea of a University (London, Imprint Academic, 2002). 12 CCCU, Our Mission and Values. See: http://www.canterbury.ac.uk/about-us/our-mission-and-values.aspx (accessed 02 June 2015) 13 CCCU, Strategic Framework 2015-2020. See: http://www.canterbury.ac.uk/about-us/docs/Strategic-Framework-2015- 2020.pdf (accessed 02 June 2015) 14 W.M. Adams, Green development: Environment and Sustainability in a Developing World, 3rd Edition (Oxon, Routledge, 2009) 15 UNESCO, United Nations Decade of Education for Sustainable Development (2005-2014): International Implementation Scheme (Paris, UNESCO, 2005). See: http://unesdoc.unesco.org/images/0014/001486/148654e.pdf (accessed 02 June 2015) 16 Banks, N. et al. Climate change and social justice: an evidence review, (York, Joseph Rowntree Foundation, 2014) See: https://www.jrf.org.uk/report/climate-change-and-social-justice-evidence-review (accessed 02 February 2016) 17 UN, Adoption of the Paris Agreement, (Paris, UN, 2015) See: https://unfccc.int/resource/docs/2015/cop21/eng/l09.pdf (accessed 22 February 2016) 18 J. Agyeman, R. Bullard and B. Evans, Just Sustainabilities: Development in an unequal world. Cambridge, Mass., MIT Press, 2003) p. 78 19 supra n. 15 20 P. Scraton, Power, Conflict and Criminalisation (London, Routledge, 2007) and law, as well as the social divisions and injustices this can propagate21. More recently zemiology, which involves a move away from a focus on crime towards a broader consideration of social harms, has demonstrated a further alignment with many of the problems which sustainable development seeks to address22. Similarly, Loader and Sparks’23 call for a public criminology which both engages with lay understandings of crime and has a greater impact on policy and practice reflects the emphasis on action and change emphasised by the sustainability movement. Green criminology with its broad focus on ecological risks and harms, wildlife crime and animal abuse24,25 is an increasingly active area of research and theorising. Perhaps the most explicit connections between criminology and sustainability are those made by Agyeman and colleagues26,27 focussing on the concept of justice. Issues of inequality and injustice can be linked to the four areas of sustainability outlined, and it is noted that “justice and sustainability are intimately linked and mutually interdependent, certainly at the problem level and increasingly at the solution level”28. The issue of ‘solutions’ is particularly poignant, for we must go beyond the talk of the harms and crimes, to transcend description and critique in order to facilitate students' understanding of “human, legal, and civil rights as well as criminal and social wrongs, resistance as well as oppression and redress as well as injustice.”29 In light of this, CfJS aims to facilitate a broad and nuanced understanding of sustainability and criminology’s potential to further it, focusing on the current ecological, cultural, socio-political and economic problems and ways of addressing them. This is done through a framework of (in)justice which allows students to embed new understanding within familiar disciplinary context and language. The module is organised around the four themes of environmental, social, economic and cultural justice, the topics of academic sessions reflecting these and covering such issues as wildlife crime, multiagency working in communities, modern slavery and rights of indigenous peoples. Incorporation of service learning through embedded volunteering forms a key part of the module, and this will be discussed at some length later on. The module was developed in 2013-14 with the support and funding from CCCU’s Futures Initiative, a strategic seed-funding and capacity development programme seeking to integrate sustainability perspectives into the curriculum30 and piloted in 2014-15. It was planned in close collaboration with the students who helped shape the subject content, teaching, learning and assessment strategies through a series of focus groups, and who then took the module the following year. As the HEA/QAA guidance31 suggests, student involvement in curriculum development can facilitate a collaborative, more democratic learning environment, creating a sense of ownership and personal responsibility, important not just for ESD but for learning in general. The students agree: 21 R.M. Unger, The Critical legal Studies Movement: Another Tine, A Greater Task (London, Verso, 2015) 22 P. Hillyard, C. Pantazis, S. Tombs and D. Gordon (eds), Beyond Criminology: Taking Harm Seriously (London, Pluto Press, 2004) 23 I. Loader and R. Sparks, Public criminology? (New York, Routledge, 2010) 24 P. Beirne and N. South, N. Issues in Green Criminology: Confronting Harms Against Environments, Humanity and Other Animals (Cullompton, Willan, 2007) 25 N. South and A. Brisman, Routledge International Handbook of Green Criminology (London, Routledge, 2012) 26 supra n. 16 27 J. Agyeman, Introducing Just Sustainabilities: Policy, Planning, and Practice (London, Zed Books, 2013) 28 supra n. 16 p. 3 29 supra n. 4 p. 34 30 P. Rands, "Five Years of the futures Initiative (2011-16), Building capacity for an uncertain world" (Canterbury, Canterbury Christ Church University, 2016). See: https://www.canterbury.ac.uk/about-us/docs/sustainability/Futures-Initiative-report- 2016.pdf 31 HEA/QAA, Education for sustainable development: Guidance for UK higher education providers (London, HEA, 2014). See: http://www.qaa.ac.uk/en/Publications/Documents/Education-sustainable-development-Guidance-June-14.pdf (accessed 02 June 2015) “Having a voice to say what you have in your education is really important because we had a chance to say what we wanted to go into a lecture, what we wanted from the assignments, which made us really motivated.” (Samantha) “It feels more personalised, you feel such a part of it whereas in other lectures you feel like you’re just a student and one of many, but then this gets you more involved.” (Charlotte) Structure of the paper Sipos and colleagues32 use Bloom’s taxonomy of cognitive, psychomotor and affective domains of learning33 in their model of ‘transformative sustainability learning’ which engages head, hands and heart. This provides the organising structure for the current paper. The ‘Head’ section briefly outlines the academic content of the module, focussing on the changes in knowledge, developing understandings of sustainability, its links to criminology and the interdisciplinary approach adopted. In the ‘Hands’ section we discuss the service-learning and volunteering elements of the module and why these are particularly suited for ESD. Links to employability are also explored. The ‘Heart’ section considers the role of critical reflection in facilitating transformative learning, and the, sometimes difficult, process of changing understandings, attitudes and behaviours ESD can initiate. Finally, we will discuss plans for future developments. Including the student voice Student involvement was key to the development and running of the module, and students’ experience provides the core for evaluating its success. Throughout, the paper uses the student voice to illustrate and evidence the different aspects of CfJS and its impact. The quotes are drawn from two sources: students’ reflective blogs which formed a key part of the assessment (see ‘Heart’ section below for more detail) and a focus group discussion conducted at the end of the module. Focus groups are well-suited for capturing understandings of any shared experience among a group of individuals34, facilitating the creation of a dialogue among participants with minimal input from the interviewer. This format also provides opportunities for consensus or disagreement among participants, illuminating significant opinions and conflicting views, made apparent here e.g. with students giving contrasting accounts of what the term sustainability means to them. Power relationships in research are often problematic and a focus group risks some participants dominating the discussion while less vocal members are overshadowed. However, the students knew each other well having been in class together each week throughout the academic year and were comfortable participating in group discussions. Similarly, as the student participants were arguably less powerful than us as facilitators and lecturers, an additional concern was over social desirability. However, 32 Y. Sipos, B. Battisti and K. Grimm, (2008). "Achieving transformative sustainability learning: engaging heads, hands and hearts" (2008) 9 International Journal of Sustainability in Higher Education 68-86. 33 B.S. Bloom, B.B. Masia and D.R. Krathwohl, Taxonomy of Educational Objectives (Two Volumes: The Affective Domain & The Cognitive Domain) (New York, NY, David McKay & Co, 1964) 34 R.D. Wimmer and J.R. Dominick, Mass Media Research: An Introduction, 9th Edition (Wadsworth, Cenage Learning, 2011) having been involved in the module development students were familiar with providing honest and constructive feedback. The focus group formed a part of a pedagogic action research study designed and conducted in adherence with the BERA Ethical Guidelines for Educational Research35. Given that the group discussion element was similar to regular class discussions and the subject matter was not sensitive, there were no significant risks of harm to the participants or the researcher. In any research project where participants are recruited coercion is a concern, and it is important to be aware that an individual’s choice about participation may be constrained36. As the students involved were all awaiting their final marks for the module, it was made clear that their decision to participate would have no positive or negative impact on these and that there were no incentives involved. Informed consent was gained through information sheets and adhering to principles of confidentiality and anonymity students were also offered pseudonyms in the writing up of the research, although all waived this right, choosing to use their real names. At the same time, consent to use students’ reflective blog entries for the purposes of this article and beyond was sought and granted. Indeed, we have been explicit in our desire to share the module experience widely and discussed the various research and publication plans openly with the students throughout the module. The response has always been one of excitement and enthusiasm. It should also be noted that the first draft of the current article was read and commented on by the students whose feedback helped to shape it further. Head: Developing Interdisciplinary Understanding A key pedagogical approach that CfJS adheres to is interdisciplinarity. Criminology, as we often describe it to our students, is a discipline that waits in the dark alley, mugs other disciplines and then searches their pockets for useful theories, concepts and methods. While its repeat victim is sociology, it also steals from psychology, economics, public administration, biology and evolutionary studies. As something that integrates rather than just adds multiple perspectives37 interdisciplinarity is therefore already a core criminological approach and explicitly embedded into CfJS’ intended learning outcomes. The content and readings which cover the four dimensions of sustainability draw heavily from beyond criminology, guest speakers from other disciplines and outside academia, and assessments all encourage students to consider the ‘bigger picture’. This section will illustrate the development of our students’ understandings of sustainability and the embedding of this within a framework of justice. Given the broad but shallow proliferation of information about the problems which sustainable development seeks to address noted earlier in this paper, all participants demonstrated some pre- existing personal interest in issues associated with the sustainability agenda, perhaps explaining their selection of the module: 35 BERA, “Ethical Guidelines for Educational Research” (London, British Educational Research Association, 2011) See: https://www.bera.ac.uk/wp-content/uploads/2014/02/BERA-Ethical-Guidelines-2011.pdf (Accessed 15 June 2015) 36 J. Mason, Qualitative Researching, 2nd Edition (London, Sage, 2002). 37 P. Jones, D. Selby and S. Sterling “More than the Sum of their Parts? Interdisciplinarity and Sustainability”, in P. Jones., D. Selby and S. Sterling (Eds.) Sustainability Education: Perspectives and Practice across Higher Education (London, Earthscan, 2010) “I watched something years ago and it was about fair trade bananas and it just really switched something on in my head.” (Laura) This example of personal consciousness regarding fair trade demonstrates an initial awareness of economic injustice, although not couched in this framework. In spite of such comments, participants all recounted being largely unfamiliar with sustainability at the beginning of the module, with statements such as “I didn’t know what [sustainability] was at all.” (Samantha) being common. When asked what awareness of this area they did have, this was largely rooted in the environmental aspects of sustainability, and answers such as ‘Pollution’ (Abbie) and ‘Climate change’ (Laura) reflected the conception that sustainability is solely a ‘green’ issue38, a notion which the module sought to both expand upon and move away from. By the end of the module the students had developed understandings of sustainability which were divergent and individualised yet overlapping and reflective of its content: “[Sustainability means] equality and making sure that everyone has equal opportunities and chance to get things.” (Charlotte) “In one of our early sessions there was that quote about how we should leave the world better than we found and it and that has stuck with me through all of the lectures, and that’s how I kind of see sustainability and can be applied to all of the strands.” (Laura) Such comments also indicate a move away from an understanding solely of the problems which sustainability seeks to address, and demonstrate a more focussed critical consideration of solutions to these problems through sustainable development. This more sophisticated academic knowledge was evidenced through the students’ observations of the connections between the various strands of sustainability studied in class: “Cultural justice, because a lot of it was protecting indigenous people but it was also people destroying their environment to make a company that was going to pollute it, so it was like social, cultural and environmental.” (Abbie) By the end of the module, we were delighted to observe that our students held a holistic and multi- faceted understanding of sustainability which reflects the integrally linked nature of the social, environmental, economic and cultural dimensions advocated by Agyeman et al.39. The overlap between criminology and the sustainable development agenda noted earlier in this paper provided a fertile ground for fostering systemic thinking which integrates, adapts, connects and complements, understands and manages complexity, and considers consequences of actions40. As well as a more nuanced understanding of sustainability, students’ awareness of the connections between this concept and criminology were apparent by the end of the module. This was in spite of initial insecurities about disciplinary boundaries which led to questions such as “how does this fit in 38 supra n. 14 39 supra n. 24 40 supra n. 2 with my degree?” (Samantha). Social justice appeared to resonate most strongly with the group, with suggesting that this aspect of the sustainability agenda was most obviously linked to their studies thus far: “I kind of find the poverty and social justice bit the most interesting so that’s the bit that I had read most about.... But I suppose you have to find out what it means to you really.” (Laura) Given the focus on issues such as social exclusion and its broader structural indicators by left realism theorists such as Jock Young41 and the tradition of attention to marginalised groups such as females and victims evidenced by early feminist and victimologist criminological perspectives, the propensity for social justice to be the most obviously relevant strand of sustainability to criminology is apparent42,43. Yet as the year progressed our students began to identify aspects of sustainable development which they felt to have a personal significance, the transformative impact of which will be discussed later in this paper, both within and beyond social justice: “With the environmental [justice] I didn’t really think anything other than climate change and then when we had stuff about wildlife crime I found that really interesting, because when I think of crime I think of it as people on people, and then the stuff about the big companies and oil and stuff, it never clicked in my head that it was criminology.” (Laura) “But it’s people that are doing these crimes and doing it to the environment has an effect on everyone else, like socially and the environment around you.” (Charlotte) These comments demonstrate real critical engagement with the intersections between crime and the problems facing the sustainable development agenda. The ability to make these connections parallels the ‘deep learning’ approach theorised by Marton and Säljö44,45. While surface learning involves absorbing information for the purpose of the task at hand, deep learning involves evaluating this knowledge and relating it to previous information in the context of the broader topic to develop a critical understanding which actively questions the material at hand. The students’ accounts demonstrated a tangible change in their awareness of sustainability and associated issues as not only relevant but integral to the criminological agenda. This was encouraging to see from our own perspective and affirmed that modules such as these which may have small beginnings can have a big impact. This also prepared and impassioned students to apply this knowledge and evaluate policy and practice in the context of their volunteering placements. 41 J. Young, The Exclusive Society: Social Exclusion, Crime and Difference in Late Modernity (London: Sage, 1999). 42 S. Schafer, The Victim and His Criminal (New York: Random House, 1968). 43 C. Smart, Women, crime, and criminology: A feminist critique (London, Routledge, 1976). 44 F. Marton, and R. Säljö “On qualitative differences in learning: 1. – Outcome and process” (1976) 46 British Journal of Educational Psychology 4. 45 F. Marton, and R. Säljö “On qualitative differences in learning: 2. Outcome as a function of the learner’s conception of the task” (1976) 46 British Journal of Educational Psychology 115. Hands: Enacting Sustainability and Learning through Service The use of experiential projects including service-learning is one of the key teaching and learning methods for ESD46. It is closely related to the ambiguous if fashionable concept of community engagement, of which student volunteering has become the most visible and easily recognisable aspect47. Such community action has a long tradition going back to the 1960s and right back to the University Settlements for the urban poor provided in the 19th and 20th centuries48. The difference is that unlike the student activism of 60s and 70s, the current initiatives are formalised and supported by the universities themselves rather than being student-led via the student unions49. Research estimates that as much as 63% of students volunteer during the course of their university degree50. It is seen to bring substantial benefits both to the students and to the communities, but these are often assumed rather than proven and the current research is limited to case studies (ibid) as is of course the current paper. It should be noted that we have not (yet) sought to evaluate the impact of students’ volunteering on their placement organisation and the discussion below therefore gauges the student, rather than community, impact. Reflecting the ESD ethos of active and service-learning, a built in volunteering placement is central to CfJS. Not only does this demonstrate a commitment to CCCU’s value of “the development of the whole person”51 by embedding employability skills and personal development within the curriculum, it also enhances the links between the university and external partner organisations. While students were responsible for arranging their own placement, the remit for this was broad provided that they were able to identify some links to justice and sustainability. The assessment for the module is comprised of three elements and integrates the volunteering placement in each. There are two pieces of written coursework: a reflective blog focussed on the student’s volunteering experience which is to be completed across the course of the academic year and a case study requiring students to critically evaluate the policies and practices of their chosen volunteering organisation in relation to theories of sustainability and justice. The final assessment is a student-led ‘end of module conference’, which required students to give a short presentation on their experience to their volunteering organisations, allowing them to gain an understanding of academic knowledge exchange. The experiences and benefits reported by the students on the CfJS module echo those of the vast majority of student volunteers52, citing significant learning and development through the volunteering placement. It was noted that embedding service learning within the module pushed students to obtain this practical experience: 46 D. Cotton and J. Winter “It’s not just Bits of Paper and Light Bulbs: A review of Sustainability Pedagogies and their Potential for use in Higher Education” in P. Jones., D. Selby and S. Sterling (Eds.) Sustainability Education: Perspectives and Practice across Higher Education (London, Earthscan, 2010) 47 C. Holdsworth and J. Quinn “Volunteering in English Higher Education” (2010) 35 Studies in Higher Education 113 48 J. Wyatt “Persistent ghosts: Romantic origins of the idea of the university communities” in I. McNay (ed) Higher education and its Communities (Buckingham, Open University Press, 2000) 49 supra n. 43 50 G. Brewis, J. Russell and C. Holdsworth, Bursting the Bubble: Students, Volunteering and the Community Research Summary (Institute for Volunteering Research, 2010) See: https://www.publicengagement.ac.uk/sites/default/files/NCCPE%20- %20Bursting%20the%20bubble.pdf (Accessed 02 June 2015) 51 supra n. 12 52 supra n. 46 “I’ve never really actually pushed myself to go out and do it [volunteer] and I thought ‘Oh, I actually have to go out and do it now’” (Charlotte) A common observation was that volunteering presented new challenges for students. While the personal developments stemming from this experience will be outlined in the subsequent section of this study, it is worth noting that for most students the focus of their selected placements was often beyond their pre-existing experiences: “I’d never worked with children before, I didn’t know what to expect. It took me a few weeks to settle in, I was some sort of new figure of authority and they wouldn’t listen to me.” (Abbie) “Some of the stuff we were told about that the offenders had done I found really difficult not to let it affect me.” (Laura) In relation to developing understandings of sustainability, participants suggested that applying the knowledge gained in class to the practical setting of their volunteering work allowed them to see how sustainability in action: “Social inclusion and making everyone feel welcome, the atmosphere there was like anyone can come or go whenever they please.” (Charlotte) “It was very difficult for me to make the connections because they weren’t as obvious. I don’t think the scouts is very justice focussed… But the longer I stayed there I kind of realised that actually they do do things to help the environment, they do do things to help inclusion, like social and cultural inclusion.” (Abbie) The second comment above suggests that even where the links to sustainability were less apparent, students were nevertheless able to make their own connections through their classroom learning to service based elements of the module. Indeed, community engagement should not be considered not as a separate ‘third mission’ of universities but as an integral part of teaching and research53, able to strengthen both through contextualisation54. “I really feel that this training tested all aspects of my education at university as well as teaching me so many new skills that I can take with me in my future career.” (Laura) The links between volunteering and employability are prominent in the current discourse. However, such instrumental emphasis on skills acquisition and future benefits can undermine the community commitment and active citizenship ethos by trivialising the inequalities or even reinforcing them by 53 P. Inman and H.G. Schuetze, “The community engagement and service mission of universities: An introduction by the editors.“ in P. Inman and H.G. Schuetze (eds.) The Community Engagement and Service Mission of Universities (Leicester, Niace, 2010). 54 H.G. Schuetze, “The ‘third mission’ of universities: Community engagement and service” in P. Inman and H.G. Schuetze (eds.) The Community Engagement and Service Mission of Universities (Leicester, Niace, 2010). positioning local communities as beneficiaries of charity55. The discourse of students receiving enhanced learning while target/local communities gain social justice is problematic as it assumes the two groups are separate, ignoring the heterogeneity within both56. CfJS sought to mitigate this in various ways. During development we worked closely with a local community network, facilitating student volunteering opportunities but also benefitting from critical input on social justice and capacity building in the local communities. The assessment strategy encouraged critical reflection on the volunteering organisations, the students’ role in them and the degree to which they furthered the different aspects of justice and sustainability. The end of module conference was attended by representatives from the students’ volunteering placements, providing an opportunity for further dialogue. The students found the approach both challenging and rewarding and the next section explores the role of critical reflection and its ability to facilitate transformational learning further. It is clear that students’ ties are often not just to the community immediate to the university. Furthermore, the developing allegiance to sustainability and community engagement as concepts and practices must be both contextualised and de-contextualised, transcending the classroom and the volunteering placement. Ideally, outcomes of such opportunities become sustainable beyond the lifespan of the module, which can act as a catalyst for individual change and long-term adaptation of sustainable practices. This is evident in our group of CfJS students, all of whom plan to continue volunteering while for some the experience is set to have even more profound consequences. One student who volunteered with children with special educational needs is considering applying for a PGCE in primary education. Another student found herself so interested and passionate about her experience of volunteering with adults with mental health problems that she applied, and was accepted, onto a Masters programme in social work. Heart: Transformational Learning through Critical Reflection While the term ‘reflection’ appears vague, Boud et al. describe it as “an important human activity in which people recapture their experience, think about it, mull it over and evaluate it”57. In the academic context the outcome is generally specific to learning, action or clarification.58 Ryan59 posits that reflection is comprised of two key elements: examination of recent experiences and reorientation of attitudes to future actions. Embedding reflection in teaching therefore has an integral transformative potential. Such personal development is gaining increasing importance in higher education, and this “emphasis on refection signals a fundamental shift in the meaning of studentship and the purposes of higher education”60. A central problem with facilitating reflection in higher education parallels the broader distinctions between ‘deep’ and ‘surface’ learning identified 55 supra n. 43 56 C. Holdsworth and J. Quinn “The Epistemological Challenge of Higher Education volunteering: “Reproductive” or “Deconstructive” Volunteering?” (2012) 44 Antipode 38. 57 D. Boud, R. Keogh and D. Walker “Promoting Reflection in Learning: A model” in D. Boud, R. Keogh and D. Walker (eds.) Reflection: Turning experience into learning (London, Kogan Page, 1985) p.19 58 J. Moon, A Handbook of Reflective and Experiential Learning (London, Routledge Falmer, 2004). 59 M. Ryan “The pedagogical balancing act: teaching reflection in higher education” (2013) 18 Teaching in Higher Education 144. 60 S. Clegg and S. Bradley “The implementation of progress files in higher education: Reflection as national policy” (2006) 51 Higher Education 465 by Marton and Säljö6162. Learner reflection is carried out at varying levels of engagement, ranging from surface level reviewing of an experience to in-depth critical reflection which is transformative in nature.6364 It is this later level which embodies Ryan’s second element, whereby future experience is reimagined and personal development takes place, reflecting ‘deep’ and transformative learning. The learning and assessment strategy of CfJS explicitly solicits reflection-on-action and reflection-in- action of the volunteering placements65. In the parlance of Willmore and Tweddell66, this is an ‘embedded elective opportunity’ where pedagogy of a specific unit of study is learning through reflective action. This brings variation to the Applied Criminology curriculum where opportunities for reflection are scarce, with one participant highlighting that “You never really do that at uni, it’s usually writing about a topic” (Charlotte). The approach allowed students who previously had no opportunity to engage in reflective writing to break from the norm, with some presenting a particular aptitude for this form of assessment and ultimately achieving higher marks. A reflective blog approach rather than a reflective essay had the advantage of requiring consistent reflection throughout the course of study rather than one final reflection after the placement, combatting the surface learning approach of learning for assessment rather than learning through it. The key benefit of a reflective blog as a learning tool is the potential to facilitate transformation through reflection which has been discussed thus far.67 Students on the module demonstrated this level of deep critical reflection in their blog entries, going beyond merely describing what happened to illustrate how this experience has been reconceptualised and will impact on future behaviour: “I can understand how easy it is to get to emotionally involve especially when you were trying to help people. I knew the boundaries and I over stepped those boundaries. When you are volunteering, you forget you have a conduct that you should follow… I do 100% take full responsibility for what has happened and have learnt from the experience and will take that experience to the next volunteer placement I chose to go to.” (Samantha) Our students noted the importance of developing these critically reflective skills. Both the focus and format of the module provided them with learning opportunities highlighted as beyond those usually available within their programme. While this paper has already touched on the merits of volunteering for applying academic knowledge and engaging with communities, the propensity for this reflection on- and in-action to facilitate deep transformative learning at a personal level must be emphasised: “I think the module’s given me a lot of skills to take away from the university with me that I haven’t got from other modules and that I would never have got from other modules.” (Abbie). 61 supra n. 40 62 supra n. 41 63 J.D. Bain, R. Ballantyne, C. Mills, N.C. Lester Reflecting on Practice: Student teachers perspectives (Flaxton, Post Pressed, 2002). 64 R. Grossman “Structures for Facilitating Student Reflection” (2008) 57 College Teaching 15. 65 D. Schön, The Reflective Practitioner (San-Francisco, CA, Jossey-Bass, 1983). 66 C. Willmore and H. Tweddell, ”Experiences of ‘Reflective Action’: forging links between student informal activity and curriculum learning for sustainability” in W. Leal Filho (ed) Transformative Approaches to Sustainable Development at Universities: World Sustainability Series. (Switzerland, Springer International Publishing, 2014) 67 R.D. Garrison and H. Kanuka “Blended learning: Uncovering its transformative potential in higher education” (2004) 7 Internet and Higher Education 95. “It helped me to understand myself a bit more and how to improve on what I’ve been doing. If I think I’ve done something not as well as I could have done, then [I’ve learned] how to change that.” (Hannah) Schön’s68 portrayal of the ‘reflective practitioner’ illustrates that reflection arguably lends itself more to disciplines which are vocational in nature and involve experiential learning. Criminological study tends not to hinge on learning through practice, making opportunities for critical reflection such as those outlined rare, yet this form of thinking is a crucial component of ESD. Cotton and Winter69 note the need for time in the curriculum for exploration, discussion and reflection of sustainability issues. This reflection should be turned inward so that we may become conscious of, clarify, challenge and de- and reconstruct values and through the process start to understand how they, together with our background and culture, shape our knowledge perceptions of the world.70 Our students noted the challenges to their understandings and in particular the heightened awareness and concern they developed surrounding some of the issues raised in the module and experienced in their volunteering placements: “I was very ignorant towards this stuff before I did the module.” (Abbie) “When she pulled up the map about how we are gonna run out of water and how we’re gonna run out of food I just thought ‘oh my god how did I not know this?’” (Laura) Throughout the course of the module, students’ learning and experiences changed their perceptions of many of the issues covered as exemplified above. Sipos et al.71 highlight that transformative sustainability learning objectives which focus on the heart aim to “impart participants with a greater sense of authority and enablement to participate as decision-makers in their socio-cultural realities”. Therefore such learning is as much about changing attitudes as it is about changing actions, particularly as habits acquired during university often become habits of a lifetime.72 The potential for transformative learning in sustainability is therefore considerable when supported by formal curriculum which provides opportunities for reflective practice7374. It is the actualisation of these changes in attitudes through the long-term embedding of sustainable practices which CfJs aims to facilitate among students, and evidence suggest that it has succeeded in doing so, at least to some extent: “The big one for me is probably don’t judge until you know. A lot of people are going through something that you probably couldn’t even imagine what they’re going through.” (Samantha) 68 supra n. 61 69 supra n. 42 70 UNESCO, Education for Sustainability, From Rio to Johannesburg: Lessons learnt from a Decade of Commitment (Paris, UNESCO, 2002) See: http://unesdoc.unesco.org/images/0012/001271/127100e.pdf (accessed 15 June 2015) 71 supra n. 28 72 supra n. 62 73 A. Ryan and D. Cotton, “Times of change: shifting pedagogy and curricula for future sustainability” in S. Sterling , L. Maxey and H. Luna (eds.) The Sustainable University Progress and prospects (Earthscan, Abingdon, 2013) 74 supra n. 62 Although increased awareness of issues such as discrimination and social equality may appear insignificant in terms of tangible impact in addressing these problems, such realignment of pre- conceived ideas about marginalised groups which challenges divisions is central to addressing such social injustice. These statements support Eyler’s notion that “Once students are heavily immersed in the complexities of a social issue, they may find that they are in a position where their old beliefs are simply not adequate for dealing with the issues.”75 Indeed, increased knowledge goes hand in hand with increased ambiguity, and the risk of cognitive dissonance: an unpleasant psychological tension arising from holding inconsistent “thoughts, attitudes, beliefs or states of awareness of behaviours.”76 This is particularly true for sustainability which challenges not just our understanding, but our values and behaviours.77 The group members were all passionate about raising awareness around the problems facing the sustainable development agenda and taking action to address these, including continuing to volunteer: “It’s made me think about things that bigger companies do that I’ve never really thought about but now I can confidently speak to someone about that.” (Laura) “It’s given me a much broader view of what actually happens in the world and what I can do to change that.” (Hannah) We have envisaged from the module’s inception that the outcomes of the opportunities provided by CfJS would become sustainable beyond the lifespan of the module, and that learning in this context would be transformative beyond the students’ usual realms of experience in university. Howatson- Jones advises students: “Writing about your experiences will help you to make sense of them, so that your understanding lasts and contributes to your lifelong learning.”78 CfJS certainly appeared to act as a catalyst for individual change and we hope that the adaptation of sustainable practices that our group have suggested is long term. Future Developments While we are extremely pleased with the impact of the module evidenced by our students thus far, the end of this pilot year provides us with an opportunity to critically reflect on our own pedagogic practice. In relation to students’ understandings of sustainability and its links to justice, their academic knowledge was clearly enhanced through the interdisciplinary and varied nature of the module content. Yet they did highlight the need for ‘more help’ (Abbie) with setting some of the specific issues discussed within the contextual framework of sustainability and justice. We will therefore endeavour to provide a more detailed introduction to these issues at the beginning of the 75 J. Eyler, J. “Reflection: Linking Service and Learning—Linking Students and Communities” (2002) 58 Journal of Social Issues 517 p. 527 76 M.A. Hogg, G.M. Vaughan, Social Psychology, 6th ed. (Harlow, Pearson Education Limited, 2011) 77 T. Ngwana “Learning and Teaching for Sustainable Development in Higher Education: Examining Dissonance and Instructional Strategy” in L. Bell, H. Stevenson and M. Neary (eds.) The Future of Higher Education: Policy, Pedagogy and the Student Experience (London, Continuum, 2009) 78 L. Howatson-Jones, Reflective Practice in Nursing, 2nd Edition (London, Sage, 2013) module. Similarly, the volunteering placements were successful in equipping students with applied knowledge and skills, yet a more structured system for monitoring students in these settings is needed. Where students encounter difficulties within their placements these ‘critical incidents’79 are opportunities for personal development, but there is also an increased need for pastoral support. Most significantly, there are of course challenges with implementing and engaging students in reflection, some of which were experienced within this module. It must be remembered that “critical reflection is not an intuitive skill”80 and students may initially struggle with this more personal form of writing. A ‘skills session’ familiarised students with reflective writing techniques, yet some of our students’ early entries evidenced more descriptive rather than critical accounts and our focus group raised a need for more regular guidance of this nature throughout the module. As well as addressing these issues, we intend to expand the module in future academic years. Owing to an increasing number of electives, sustainability modules are often in competition with other specialist areas, instead of being seen as something that overarches and connects them and the number of students enrolled on them is comparatively low.81 CfJS only attracted five students in its first year, most of whom were also involved in the module development which was highlighted as a key benefit. Students undertaking the module in 2015-16 are currently engaged in pre-module focus groups to discuss potential new content, an aspect of CfJS which we plan to continue. We hope that as the module becomes established within the school it will recruit more widely rather than being viewed by students as too different; something outside their comfort zone and prior learning, too risky especially during final year when degree classification concerns are paramount82. There is also scope to enhance sustainability focus within the criminological curriculum beyond the CfJS optional module format. Without significantly expanding programme content in an often already crowded core curriculum, increased embedding of the language of sustainability in core modules, for example in areas such as critical criminology or legal studies, would highlight the links to a wider range of students. At CCCU an ESD curriculum mapping tool has been developed to aid the process across all academic programmes, while an extracurricular project exploring the criminal justice and sustainability links in particular has proved another successful approach.83 As well as highlighting the links for students, this would also evidence the centrality of sustainability in a variety of disciplines to academics themselves who may in turn reflect on where sustainability fits within their programmes. A further potential for development is the opportunity to evaluate CfJS’ impact on volunteering organisations in the coming years. While we were able to speak with representatives informally at the end of year module conference, a more structured approach such as a survey would provide valuable feedback and further emphasise the centrality of connecting the university and community to the module. 79 supra n. 70 80 supra n. 55 p.154 81 A. McGoshan and S.Martin, From strategy to implementation: the second evaluation of the Green Academy programme (HEA, 2014) See: https://www.heacademy.ac.uk/sites/default/files/resources/2nd_Green_Academy_Evaluation_2014_FINAL.pdf (accessed 02 June 2015) 82 Ibid. 83 K.M. Hallenberg and M. Tennant, 'Criminology Picks Up the Gauntlet: Responses to the Whole Earth? Exhibition' (Inspire: HEA Annual Social Sciences Conference, Manchester, UK, 3-4 December 2015) Conclusions “Even if you do something really small it can have a big effect.” (Hannah) CfJS is part of a deliberately grassroots level approach to embedding sustainability and changing culture through the cumulative effect of individual projects that CCCU has adopted.84 Indeed, modules that explicitly address sustainability bear both strategic and symbolic relevance.85 They not only signal the importance of sustainability to their discipline, programme and institution, but can also act as an example and catalyst for change, particularly where sustainability considerations have not previously been explicitly, or at all, addressed. 86 CfJS has adopted an openly critical pedagogy approach, aimed to challenge practices and discourses, in education but particularly in the wider social, economic and political sphere, that reproduce inequalities and social injustice.87 Within criminal justice, the approach problematizes the concepts of crime and deviance, highlighting their historically and socially contingent nature, the role of the state and its agencies, and brings voice to those at the receiving end of their practices.88 CfJS encourages the students, and staff, to listen. For the students, CfJS has clearly been an enriching experience in terms of knowledge, understanding and skills gained. It has been gratifying to witness the growing appreciation of sustainability, changing attitudes and behaviours, and the increasing enthusiasm through class interactions and reflective blogs. But such learning and development are not confined to the students. For us, the module has been a highly challenging and highly rewarding experience both professionally and personally. As educators, it has been wonderful to work with such an engaged group of students, to witness such transformation in them, and to have an opportunity to critically reflect on our own practice through the challenges an atypical module such as this brings. As academics it has been gratifying to challenge and stretch our own knowledge and understanding when it comes to the various dimensions of sustainability and justice, and to increase professional networks in this area. Moving forward, we hope that through this module we can encourage other academics to reflect on where ESD may fit for them and to recognise its interdisciplinarity. On a personal note, we have experienced the module as immensely enjoyable and downright fun, and when you can say that about your work, you are onto a winner! “Education will need to prioritize the development of those dynamic capacities – cognitive, interpersonal and motivational – associated with the ability to continuously shape and reshape one’s own existence”89 84 S. Scoffham and N. Kemp “It’s Contagious! Developing sustainability perspectives in academic life at a UK university” in W. L. Filho, U. M. Azeiteiro, S. Caeiro & F. Alves (eds) Integrating Sustainability Thinking in Science and Engineering Curricula: Innovative Approaches, Methods and Tools (London, Springer, 2015) 85 supra n. 76 86 Ibid. 87 P. Freire, Pedagogy of the oppressed (London, Continuum, 1996). 88 supra n. 4 89 J. Eliot “The Curriculum Experiment: Meeting the Challenge of Social Change” in W. Scott and S. Gough (eds) Key Issues in Sustainable Development and Learning: A Critical Review (London, Routledge Falmer, 2004) For all of us involved in CfJS the experience has done just that, transforming our understanding of and relationship with each other and the world that we live and learn in. We are happy that Samantha’s wish… “I think this is a module that should continue at CCCU and hope other students benefit from the module as much as I have.” …is granted and the module continues to run. work_27a4tagqjzb5tojpe7qq4fpjou ---- Tilburg University Weighting justice Gramatikov, M.A.; Laxminarayan, M.S. Publication date: 2008 Document Version Early version, also known as pre-print Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): Gramatikov, M. A., & Laxminarayan, M. S. (2008). Weighting justice: Constructing an index of access to justice. (TISCO Working Paper Series; Vol. 010/2008). Tilburg Institute for Interdisciplinary Studies of Civil Law and Conflict Resolution Systems (TISCO). http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1344418 General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal ? Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 06. apr. 2021 https://research.tilburguniversity.edu/en/publications/57e87b44-dbcc-4774-af14-dc749d49213e http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1344418 1 TISCO WORKING PAPER SERIES ON CIVIL LAW AND CONFLICT RESOLUTION SYSTEMS Weighting Justice: Constructing an Index of Access to Justice Martin Gramatikov Tilburg University Tilburg Institute for Interdisciplinary Studies of Civil Law and Conflict Resolution Systems (TISCO, Hague Institute for the Internationalisation of Law (HIIL) m.a.gramatikov@uvt.nl & Malini Laxminarayan Tilburg University Tilburg Institute for Interdisciplinary Studies of Civil Law and Conflict Resolution Systems (TISCO), Hague Institute for the Internationalisation of Law (HIIL) M.S.Laxminarayan@uvt.nl TISCO Working Paper Series on Civil Law and Conflict Resolution Systems No. 10/2008 Month December 2008, Version: 1.0 & Tilburg University Legal Studies Working Paper No. 18/2008 This paper can be downloaded without charge from the Social Science Research Network Electronic Paper Collection 2 I. Legal indexes ............................................................................................................. 3 II. Measuring access to justice ....................................................................................... 5 A. Usefulness of the index.......................................................................................... 6 B. Access to justice indicators .................................................................................... 8 III. Weighting the index items ........................................................................................ 11 A. Sample weights.................................................................................................... 11 B. Item weights ......................................................................................................... 12 1. Stated preferences weights ................................................................................. 13 2. Extracted association weights.............................................................................. 13 3. Advantages and disadvantages of weighting the items ....................................... 14 IV. Three examples of weighting items ..................................................................... 15 A. Stated preferences weights ................................................................................. 15 B. Association weights extracted with factor analysis .............................................. 16 C. Association weights extracted with multiple regression ....................................... 17 D. Using un- weighted data ...................................................................................... 19 V. Application of weights .......................................................................................... 19 VI. Index validation .................................................................................................... 22 VII. Conclusion ........................................................................................................... 23 Appendix A: Methodology for data collection ................................................................... 25 Appendix B: Computation of weights ............................................................................... 27 Abstract The methods and procedures for measuring the performance of a legal system are debatable issues. Legal indexes, although not common, do exist as a means for measurement and evaluation of various legal phenomena. This paper outlines one method using the Access to Justice Index, which is a procedure for aggregating the relevant data on the costs, the quality of the procedure and the quality of the outcome of a given legal path. This data is a result of the various justice theories that measure experiences of the user when attempting to solve a dispute. The paper investigates in detail the need for and applicability of weights in order to adjust the observed data. After assessing the possible methods of extracting and applying weights, we conclude that factor analysis is in fact the most practical and reliable technique. The option of non-weighting is also briefly considered, and sheds light on the possibility for leaving the data in its original form. The paper concludes with a discussion on the validation of the index and a case study of consumer disputes in the Netherlands to illustrate its performance. 3 “If you cannot measure it, you cannot improve it” Lord Kelvin I. Legal indexes Different factors fuel the growing need for the measurement of legal phenomena. Globalization and worldwide competition, universal character of human rights, ‘judicial borrowing’, and donors’ investments in legal reforms are only a few of these factors. How to measure the performance of a legal system is a contentious issue. Looking at the inputs of the system could provide some knowledge on the general legal infrastructure, but the input-based approach could, at best, provide an approximation for the performance levels. The outcomes of the legal system are a more valid representation of its ability to solve problems, provide legal certainty and reinforce the social order. Again, the question remains what set of indicators better gauges the outcomes of a legal system. A popular approach to assess the outcome is to concentrate on the Rule of Law (RoL) paradigm. The RoL, however, is a complex and unobservable part of the social world. Its existence and strength could be judged only after an assessment of numerous indicators, including independence of the judiciary, equal and consistent application of the law to similar cases, and accountability of the government. Accessibility of the national justice systems or accessibility of a single dispute resolution procedure is a particularly powerful indicator of the fairness, effectiveness, and inclusiveness of the legal systems. Access to justice, however, is also a complex phenomenon consisting of different aspects and meanings. These phenomena could vary across time, jurisdiction, social class or legal culture. One plausible strategy to measure such a rich and diverse domain is to use a set of standard indicators. Each individual indicator would measure separate parts of the general concept. In order to cast light on the whole, rather than on parts, the indicators should be combined into an index. Every index has two general purposes – integration and parsimony1. Integration requires the sum of the parts to provide more knowledge than individual parts. For instance, the World Bank’s Worldwide Governance Indicators (WGI) combines a vast amount of individual indicators together to assess the level of governance in the national states2. In real life, however, governance is only a vague concept which cannot be observed and measured directly. The theory of the indicators states that it is an observable phenomenon, which could be assessed by looking at observable sub- indicators or markers. The WGI distinguish six dimensions of the governance, one of which is the RoL. It is a complex and unobservable phenomenon defined as “....the extent to which agents have confidence in and abide by the rules of society, and in 1 ELIZABETHANN O'SULLIVAN & GARY R. RASSEL, Research Methods for Public Administrators (Longman Third Edition ed. 1999); LEA BISHOP SHAVER, Defining and Measuring A2K: A Blueprint for an Index of Access to Knowledge, 4 I/S: A Journal of Law and Policy for the Information Society 235, (2008). 2 DANIEL KAUFMANN, et al., Governance Matters VII: Aggregate and Individual Governance Indicators, 1996-2007 available at http://ssrn.com/paper=1148386. 4 particular the quality of contract enforcement, property rights, the police, and the courts, as well as the likelihood of crime and violence”3. Apparently, the enforcement of contracts and the likelihood of crime measure different things on different scales. However, the WGI team believes that these are aspects of the higher-level RoL concept, and, thus, treats their scores as parts of the composite index. Therefore, the purpose of the index is to integrate the different parts of the whole into a single value. Dealing with one representation of the idea of RoL instead of with its dimensions provides parsimony – clarity and a simplified explanation of the observations. Similarly, Freedom House collects data and computes its Freedom in the World Index4. RoL is considered an important dimension in the broader idea of freedom. As in the WGI, the Rule of Law is treated as a complex phenomenon which can only be observed through proxy indicators. Independency of the judiciary, civic control over police, the extent of legal protection against external intrusions, and fairness of the law are the four ingredients of the RoL, according to the theoretical framework of Freedom House. Each of these ingredients is put into operation through a set of items in which data is collected. In order to integrate the fragments of the RoL concept, researchers combine the items into higher-order dimensions. The dimensions are then aggregated into a composite index which provides information on the level of the RoL in a particular country. Several other global or regional indexes measuring legal constructs are related to access to justice5. The Heritage Foundation measures economic freedom. One of the components of this index is the property rights defined as an “an assessment of the ability of individuals to accumulate private property, secured by clear laws that are fully enforced by the state”6 . The American Bar Association World Justice Project develop and test an index, which aims to measure the countries’ adherence to the RoL7. Four broad factors (called bands) are contemplated as proxies of the index, with the third band closely connected to the accessibility of the justice system. Its content is described as “...the accessibility, fairness and efficiency of the process by which the laws are enacted, administered and enforced”8. In this paper, we discuss the substance and the procedure for computation of the Access to Justice Index. Both aspects are of critical importance for the usefulness of the index. A rigorously computed index of data which does not properly represent the measured idea may end up being a worthless use of time and resources. The opposite is also true – even if the data validly measure components of access to justice, a 3 Id. at 7. 4 FREEDOM HOUSE, Freedom in the World 2007: The Annual Survey of Political Rights and Civil Liberties (Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. 2007). 5 See more on global and regional indexes that measure legal phenomena can be found in CHRISTIANE ARNDT & CHARLES OMAN, Uses and abuses of governance indicators (Development Centre of the Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development. 2006). 6 KIM R. HOLMES, et al., 2008 Index of Economic Freedom 41 (The Heritage Foundation 2008). 7 See http://www.abanet.org/wjp/ 8 THE WORLD JUSTICE PROJECT, Rule of Law Principles and World Justice Project Overview. (2008), at http://www.abanet.org/wjp/docs/abawjpresourcekit.pdf. 5 flawed index construction will cast doubts on the outcome. In order to mitigate these challenges, we will first review the substantial part of the index. All three indicators will briefly be introduced and explained. Then, alternative options for the aggregation of these parts into one composite index will be investigated. The options will be tested on a data set from a survey of the path to justice in the Netherlands. In chapter 1, the concept of an index and the content and formulation of some of the most popular legal indexes were discussed. The remainder of the paper proceeds as follows: The second part of the paper examines the decisions that have to be made in order to aggregate the pieces of data into one index. Special emphasis is given to the issue of weighing the data. In addition, three alternative strategies to derive weights for the quality of the procedure and the quality of outcome will be discussed. The options will then be applied to the observed data in order to study the impact of the weights. Finally, we discuss a strategy for assessing the validity of the composite index. II. Measuring access to justice In the last decades, a growing number of studies have applied theories and methods from humanities, social sciences and economics to understand different legal phenomena. Access to justice is one of the legal domains that gathered significant inter-disciplinary attention. Increasingly, the accessibility of the legal systems, and in particular the dispute resolution systems, are measured through quantitative methods. Since the 1970s, researchers employed empirical strategies to estimate the legal needs that exist in society9. In these early studies, legal needs were expected to fall under the category of professional legal advice. Although from different viewpoints, access to justice is quantitatively examined in studies measuring the costs and delay of litigation procedures10. Access to justice has been measured in varying ways, often dependant on the discipline carrying out the research. Psychologists focus on the procedural and distributive justice needs of users11, while economists are more interested in the costs associated with a given procedure. Victimologists are concerned with the negative repercussions crime victims suffer while gaining access to justice12. For economists, social scientists and lawyers alike, there is a desire to link access to justice to those 9 AMERICAN BAR ASSOCIATION, Comprehensive Legal Needs Study. (1994); BARBARA A. CURRAN, The Legal Needs of the Public: The Final Report of A National Survey (American Bar Foundation. 1977). 10 HERBERT M. KRITZER, et al., Understanding the Costs of Litigation: The Case of the Hourly Fee Lawyer, Summer 1984 American Bar Foundation Research Journal 559, (1984); DAVID M. TRUBEK, et al., The Costs of Ordinary Litigation, 31 UCLA L. Rev. 72, (1983); EDGAR LIND, et al., The Perception of Justice. Tort Litigants' Views of Trial, Court-Annexed Arbitration, and Judicial Settlement Conferences (1989). 11 S. ALEXANDER & M. RUDERMAN, The role of procedural and distributive justice in organizational behavior, 1 Social Justice Research, (1987); LAURA KLAMING & IVO GIESEN, Access to Justice: The Quality of the Procedure available at http://ssrn.com/paper=1091105; JOHN THIBAUT & LAURENS WALKER, Procedural justice: A psychological analysis (Erlbaum. 1975). 12 ULI ORTH, Secondary Victimization of Crime Victims by Criminal Proceedings, 15 Social Justice Research, (2002); JOANNA SHAPLAND, et al., Victims in the criminal justice system (Gower. 1985). 6 suffering from social inequality. Other topics of interest include informal justice methods, access to legal aid and public interest law13. In the 1990s, research on access to justice shifted towards the direction of broader inquiry on the sociological aspects of access to justice. In an influential study, Professor Hazel Genn surveyed the response strategies to non-trivial problems that might have a resolution with legal means14. The so-called “justiciable events methodology” gained popularity and has been replicated over time and jurisdictions15. Its power is based on a comprehensive assessment of the impact that legal problems have in everyday life. What the “justiciable” research methodology still cannot deliver, however, is a comparison of the results across jurisdictions. Although the inferences are based on perception-based data, the various research projects split into different categories, including types of problems, period of interest and data collection method. A different approach to the quantitative assessment of access to justice is proposed by the “Measuring Access to Justice” (MA2J) project16. The project develops a research methodology which measures access to justice through the perceptions and attitudes of people who have travelled a path to justice. As compared with the justiciable events studies, the MA2J diverges significantly – its units of measurement are individuals who had a legal problem and acted to solve it with the means of state or non-state intervention. In fact, three major aspects of the experiences of the users are measured – the costs of justice17, the quality of the procedure18 and the quality of the outcome19. Each of these three pillars of the user’s experiences is modelled as a multi- faceted indicator consisting of sub-indicators. The individual scores of the sub- indicators form the scores of the three higher level indicators. At the next level, the project intends to aggregate the information on costs, quality of the procedure and quality of the outcome into one composite figure. This single value, the Access to Justice Index, should provide focused information about the measured paths to justice. A. Usefulness of the index First, we should clearly state the reasons for the index and its usefulness in examining procedures individually and in comparison to another. Individual evaluation may offer 13 MAURITS BARENDRECHT, et al., How to Measure the Price and Quality of Access to Justice? available at http://ssrn.com/paper=949209. 14 HAZEL GENN, Paths to Justice. What people do and think about going to law? (Hart Publishing. 1999). 15 AB CURRIE, The Legal Problems of Everyday Life (2007);HAZEL GENN & ALAN PATERSON, Paths to Justice Scotland. What People in Scotland Do and Think About Going to Law (Hart Publishing. 2001);PASCOE PLEASENCE, et al., Causes of Action: Civil Law and Social Justice (Stationery Office. 2004);MARTIN GRAMATIKOV, Multiple Justiciable Events in Bulgaria (Legal Services Research Centre ed., 2008);BEN C. J. VAN VELTHOVEN & MARIJKE TER VOERT, Paths to Justice in the Netherlands. Looking for signs of social exclusion. 28 (2004). 16 BARENDRECHT, et al., supra note 13; MARTIN GRAMATIKOV, et al., Measuring the Costs and Quality of Paths to Justice: Contours of a Methodology (SSRN 2008). 17 MARTIN GRAMATIKOV, A Framework for Measuring the Costs of Access to Justice, 2 J. Juris. 111, (2009). 18 KLAMING & GIESEN, supra note 11. 19 JIN HO VERDONSCHOT, et al., Measuring Access to Justice: The Quality of Outcomes available at http://ssrn.com/paper=1298917. 7 less information than comparative values, but insights can still arise concerning the need for improvement. Furthermore, the aim of the index is – once data has been collected and analyzed – to compile rankings of procedures in a relatable manner. Understanding what is relatable or comparable (between jurisdictions or between procedures) will be elaborated on below. Using these evaluations and comparisons can lead to policy implications; the index can serve as a learning tool among jurisdictions. Evaluation The idea behind indexes is simple: to summarize several indicators into one numerical score. One objective of the index is for the evaluation of a given procedure. If a neutral is concerned with user perceptions of his or her procedure, the index can provide numerous insights into the various components of the process. Furthermore, if a user is curious about a given procedure, and has access to this information, he or she may obtain a better understanding of what lies ahead. Although costs may be higher in one case, a more favourable outcome may outweigh this shortcoming. Each component can be compared with the use of the sub-indexes. In addition, this evaluation can be used for comparisons and policy evaluations, as we will discuss. Comparison Both comparisons among countries or paths and comparisons over time can offer various policy implications. Comparison over time can illustrate whether or not there have been improvements in certain procedures. For example, in the field of victimology, legal provisions have recently taken place and will continue to do so at both national and supranational levels. The effects of these changes can be measured by victim satisfaction and their perceptions of the quality of the experiences, and, consequently, the rankings conferred to various procedures. Legislation reform can be established in one jurisdiction; actual implementation, however, may paint a much different picture. This notion can be illustrated by one example in the Dutch criminal justice system. In the past decade, various guidelines (as stated by the 1995 Terwee Act)20 have been established which improve information (informational justice items), participation (procedural justice items), and treatment of victims21 (interpersonal justice items). In this instance, not having only one composite index, but instead several sub-indexes for each type of justice, will prove to be an advantage. Furthermore, longitudinal studies using these indexes would provide for valuable insights into the policies which have been established. More attention can be devoted to those areas which may be lacking acceptable values. Understandably, the index will not be valuable unless legal problems are either similar between different paths in the same country or similar legal problems between countries follow the same paths. For example, labour issues in the Netherlands will not be compared to consumer disputes in Belgium. Rather, the aim is to extract weights (discussed in detail in the latter part 20 Wet Terwee, Victim Act Terwee, Gazette 1995, no. 65., incorporated in the Dutch Code of Criminal Procedure of 15 January 1921, Stb. 14, amended 6 December 1995, Stb. 592 21 MARION ELEONORA INGEBORG BRIENEN & ERNESTINE HENRIËTTE HOEGEN, Victims of crime in 22 European criminal justice systems : the implementation of Recommendation (85) 11 of the Council of Europe on the Position of the Victim in the Framework of Criminal Law and Procedure : proefschrift (Wolf Legal Productions (WLP)/Vidya in cooperation with the Global Law Association. 2000). 8 of this paper) for each path to justice, and, consequently, draw conclusions from those paths which are in fact comparable. Comparable data has further implications for policy changes, suggesting that countries have the ability to look to each other’s legal systems and procedures for administering justice. B. Access to justice indicators Our theory of the Access to Justice Index is based on the belief that the users’ perspective is appropriate ground for assessing the extent of accessibility. A focus on the experiences of the users of justice means that the units of analysis are particular paths to justice. All conclusions and inferences will be applicable to the measured path to justice. Our definition of a path to justice is “a commonly applied process which users of justice address in order to cope with their justice needs”22. Both formal and informal processes could be positioned under the broad scope of the definition of a path to justice. A path begins when the user first addresses the process. This first active and deliberative involvement of the user into the process could be explicated through different acts – searching for information, acceptance of advice, filing documents, etc. The path ends when the user receives an outcome from the process. An outcome could be a final decision by a mediator, a joint agreement of the parties, or an end to the process because one of the parties quits. The experiences of the users of justice are measured against three indicators: the costs of the procedure, the quality of the procedure, and the quality of the outcome. Each indicator is built by a complex structure of sub-indicators. For instance, the costs of the procedure are defined as the resources, which the user would need to travel from the beginning to the end of a path to justice. Within this indicator, a set of sub- indicators reflect different types of procedural costs: out-of-pocket expenses, time, and other opportunity and intangible costs (stress, emotions, etc.). Similarly, the two quality indicators consist of lower level sub-indicators that measure its specific facets. 22 MARTIN GRAMATIKOV, Methodological Challenges in Measuring Cost and Quality of Access to Justice available at http://ssrn.com/paper=1099392. 9 Figure 1: Access to Justice Index Figure 1 outlines the components of the Access to Justice Index. In the table below we outline the sub-indicators of access to justice in more detail. An elaboration of these concepts can be found in relevant papers23. Important to note, however, is that not all indicators are universal across users. To give an example, while indicators of utilitarianism may be applicable to users of the criminal justice system, the same may not hold true for other legal problems. Table 1: Indicators of the Costs and Quality of Paths to Justice Costs of the Procedure Indicator Description Examples Out-of-pocket expenses The monetary amount spent on transactions during and as a result of the proceedings Lawyer fees, expert fees, filing fees, transportation fees, bailiff and witness fees, notary fees, costs for communication Time Time spent dealing with the procedure Searching for a legal advisor, collecting information, contacting professionals, travelling, awaiting/attending hearings, waiting in queues Other lost opportunities The cost of lost opportunities due to the proceedings and their possible lengthiness Lost income, devaluated resources, losing a job opportunity Intangible costs On their paths to justice, people tend to expend emotions, suffer stress, Stress, negative emotions such as frustration, fear, disappointment or anger, loss of relationships 23 KLAMING & GIESEN, supra note 11; GRAMATIKOV, supra note 17; VERDONSCHOT, et al., supra note 19; MALINI LAXMINARAYAN, Measuring Crime Victim’s Paths to Justice: Developing Indicators for Costs and Quality of Access to Justice (Tilburg University 2008). 10 become depressed or experience deterioration in their relationships with significant others Quality of the procedure Indicator Description Sub-indicators Procedural Justice Fairness perceptions of users regarding the processes that are utilized to resolve disputes and allocate resources Process control, decision control, consistency, bias suppression, accuracy, ability to correct, ethicality Restorative Justice Concerned with the harm that has been caused by the legal problem and attempts to offer reparation to the user of justice Opportunity to ask the other party for an explanation and recognition Interpersonal Justice The extent to which people are treated with politeness, respect, and propriety Politeness, respect, propriety, respect for rights Informational Justice The validity of information provided by decision makers as the foundation of the decision making process Honesty, explanation of rights and options, as well as whether the explanation was timely, understandable, and in need of clarification Quality of the Outcome Indicator Description Sub-Indicators Distributive Justice The allocation of resources among individuals with competing needs or claims Equity, equality, need Corrective (compensatory) Justice When one person is wrongfully injured by another, the injurer must make the harmed party whole Compensation Restorative Justice Looks to the future and the best means to achieve reparation of harm, including elements of apology, shame and repair of relationships Opportunity given to the offender to show remorse and to accept responsibility, the degree of reparation of emotional and monetary harms, closure, alleviation of fear Retributive Justice An infliction of proportionate loss and pain to the injurer is necessary to achieve justice Just deserts Utilitarianism Social harmony can be attained via the prevention of future harm Deterrence and incapacitation Informational Justice The validity of information provided by decision makers Outcome justification 11 as the foundation of the decision making process Transformative Justice The future is a main concern, in addition to transformations with the self, self-in-relationships, and self-in-society Considering parties’ interests and re-building relationships Legal pragmatism Concerned with facts and consequences Pragmatic outcome, consequences taken into account Formal Justice Similar cases are defined by the situation, not the person – i.e., treat similar cases alike Similar outcomes and ability to compare outcomes with related others III. Weighting the index items One way to compute the Access to Justice Index is to aggregate the values of all items, thus measuring a higher-order concept. The outcome means will reflect the score of the unobservable variables. At the next level, the same computation could be performed in order to discover the scores of the three basic indicators (costs, quality of the procedure, and quality of the outcome). In a third round of aggregation, the composite index of the accessibility of the measured path to justice could be estimated through the mean of the three main indicators. Such a routine uses the non-weighted original values of the items. It assumes that the data reliably measures the indicators allowing the studied sample to formulate reliable inferences. Alternatively, the two assumptions discussed above may be relaxed. They could either be uncertain that the instrument items measure the concepts of interest well, or the sample deviates systemically from the population. In both cases, weights could be used for adjusting the original values. In essence, the weighting is a procedure of assigning different degrees of importance to the original data depending on additional information. In this chapter, we review the possible alternatives for deriving and applying weights to the items and indicators of the Access to Justice Index. A. Sample weights The weights could reflect three distinct aspects of the reliability of the index components. Most often, weights are used to adjust the sample toward some known characteristics of the population of interest. In order to adjust the sample data, underrepresented groups are weighted more heavily in order to influence the data in proportion to their participation in the population. The focus of this paper, however, is on item weights and how this procedure can be achieved. 12 B. Item weights Weighting items is more challenging, as it attempts to collectively measure an unobservable indicator. In the case of the sample adjustment, the weights are applied to decrease the differences between the sample and the population from which it has been drawn. Weights could also be applied to the items of the research instrument. The logic of this type of weighting lies in the unknown importance of the items. Our theoretical framework determines what items are likely to measure an indicator, but it does not indicate how well each item performs. When we measure the costs and quality of a path to justice, we hypothesize that the users use the criteria set out in Figure 1. However, we do not know whether the distributive justice impacts the perception of the procedure quality more than the informational justice. It is an empirical question to ascertain the magnitude of importance of these criteria. The assumption that items and indicators could vary in their importance calls for an estimation of the parameters of such importance. But what exactly does importance of an item for measuring justice indicators mean? Two principally different answers could be given to this question. First, subjective importance implies that the particular users of justice have a preference scale on which they estimate the relationships between items. Thus, parties in two different types of legal processes may have different preferences for the criteria used to measure the quality of the outcome. For instance, depending on circumstances and personal preferences, the user could place greater value on the distributive or informational aspects of the outcome. These weights are further referred to as stated preferences weights. A second method to answering the estimation question takes a radically different approach. Instead of searching for the answer in the users’ preference scales, it assumes a more theoretical stance. After the important indicators are into items, this second approach attempts to discover how well the items measure the unobservable indicator. In a sense, it disregards the personal preferences, instead relying on the validity of the measurement tool. For brevity, the weights that reflect the connection with the unobservable indicator will be called extracted association weights. Both approaches for justifications of item weights will be discussed below. Their advantages and disadvantages could be studied on two levels. One is the conceptual level, where it must be decided which approach is more coherent with the research questions that the Access to Justice Index must answer. The two weighting paradigms reflect different technique of uncovering the importance of the items. One method is based on personal choice; the other is grounded in the ability of the item to measure the latent construct. Apart from the theoretical differences, the rationale of the two approaches must also be assessed from an empirical perspective. Item weights are not easy to operationalize, measure, and interpret. Often, estimation of item weights requires complicated research designs and procedures. The reliability of the outcomes of the weight extraction is of major concern, and thus should be factored into the discussion of the advantages and disadvantages of the stated preferences weights and the extracted association weights. 13 1. Stated preferences weights Weights based on the stated preferences regarding the relative importance of an item assume that users place different levels of importance on individual items. For instance, the restorative effect of the outcome could be more significant than its distributive consequences. Or, at another level, the quality of the procedure could be more important than the quality of the outcome. It is possible that the importance function is dependent on the personal characteristics of the respondent. However, it could also be that preferences are influenced by belonging to social groups, types of problems, or types of procedures. People from different social groups could systematically place dissimilar preferences on individual indicators. Economic position, education or political views could interact with the preferences on the items that measure costs and quality of paths to justice. It is a plausible hypothesis that for those with more resources, the quality of the procedure matters more than that of the outcome. Alternatively, the less fortunate will value the outcome more because of the higher marginal utility. These hypotheses, however, could prove useless because of the many possible interactions between individual characteristics and perceptions on the justice. For instance, people with more resources normally tend to have a better education and know more about their rights. As such, they could place even stronger emphasis on the quality of the outcome. The importance of the items may also be impacted by the type of process used. State organized paths to justice are more formal, causing users to focus more on the need to receive attention and empathy from the neutral. More legal formalism increases duration and costs of dispute resolution, which could mean that costs will be of utmost importance. On non-state paths, such as negotiations or mediation, the quality of the outcome could be perceived by users as being more important. 2. Extracted association weights Many of the indicators for measuring access to justice cannot be observed directly and have to be measured through proxy indicators. While each of the proxy variables captures part of the unobservable variable of interest, they may also reflect other facts and perceptions. Some of the items will measure a larger share of the indicator and, therefore, will be better associated with it. The weight of the items could also be based on their abilities to measure the indicator. For instance, we measure interpersonal justice with four items, and it is highly unlikely that these four items contain an equal amount of information on the unobserved factor. If the quality of the procedure is believed to consist of three components (procedural justice, interpersonal justice, and informational justice), it would be very bold to assume that they participate equally in it. It is entirely possible that one of the items24 is better associated with the quality of the outcome. Weights, based on the association of the item with the unobservable indicators, should assign more importance on this item and less importance on the others. 24 These are already aggregated items. 14 Using extracted association weights, the researcher has more influence on the weighting process. The items’ weights depend on the relationship (association) of the item and the unobservable indicator. In order to discover the strength and the direction of the association, the index constructor has to extract the weights. As we saw above, in the stated preferences weights, it is the user of justice (the respondent) who directly determines the weights. 3. Advantages and disadvantages of weighting the items Preference of one of the options for extraction of weights should be guided by theoretical and practical considerations. It is likely that both weights are applied to different parts of a measurement tool. For instance, in the Access to Justice Index, both weighting schemes could be used to increase the reliability of the composite index. Below is an example of a theoretically driven choice of weights. The theory is grounded in the characteristics and linkages of the index indicators described above. At the bottom level of the index (Figure 1), where the unobservable criteria are measured by proxy variables, the use of extracted association weights will be more feasible. All proxy-variables are supposed to measure a relatively compact indicator, and it would be difficult for the users of justice to clearly differentiate which item is more important in relation to the others. Application of the extracted association weights relieves the users from the burden of making a difficult choice, and indicates which item is better associated with the unobservable indicator. Thus, the adjustment of the significance of items according to their ability to measure the indicator has sound theoretical fundaments. An example follows: In the quality of the procedure dimension, the index has four complex indicators. Another eight indicators measure the quality of the outcome (Figure 1). Again, a decision must be made on which weighting scheme to use at this second level of aggregation. The application of extracted association weights is an option, but there is one serious concern. Each of the items is a product of the lower level items. If one wants to find out how the four items measure the quality of the procedure, she must consider the fact that these items inhibit more measurement error due to the aggregation process. Alternatively, the stated preference weights could be used to improve the reliability at the second level of the index. This means that users should indicate the importance of each of the aggregated items against each other. An item in which the respondents are asked to rate its importance could provide a meaningful preference weight. The disadvantage of this approach is the need for clear operationalization of the aggregated items. Asking respondents about procedural justice, restorative justice, or other highly abstract terms will likely impact the validity of the instrument. Therefore, the use of importance weights could be recommended only when the indicators of interest can be sufficiently explained in a language that will be understood clearly by the respondents. As stated above, the choice of weights for index items should also be guided by practical considerations. Computing the weights of items requires additional resources in terms of increased samples and larger questionnaires. The stated preferences 15 weights seem to be significantly more challenging. Either the respondents have to reveal their preferences together with the items, or the preferences should be obtained from a different source. While the former approach is appealing, it could undermine the reliability of the measurement. A research instrument which asks for the importance of each item will double its size, inevitably leading to lower response rates and other negative effects. Even more challenging is the extraction of weights from different sources. Later, we discuss the pros and cons of estimating weights in one sample and applying them to the item scores of another. An interesting related question is whether universal weights could exist for paths to justice. A theory of universal weights must build on the assumption that users of particular paths to justice have stable preferences on the evaluation criteria. Apparently, this assumption should be limited at different levels, such as type of problem, characteristics of the parties, specifics of the particular jurisdiction, the related legal culture, etc. Unlike the stated preferences weights, the extracted association weights are less demanding in terms of research resources. Normally, the observed data could be easily analyzed with statistical techniques, such as factor analysis or multivariate regression. Below, we give three examples for extraction and application of weights. IV. Three examples of weighting items A. Stated preferences weights In a quasi-experiment, we obtained the stated preferences of users of justice on the importance of the quality of the procedure and the quality of the outcome indicators25. A direct result of the measurement is that it provides a hierarchical order, which reflects the subjective importance of the individual items. An item which is ranked as the most significant (e.g. voice) within a group of items (e.g. procedural justice) is deemed as more important than the other items from the same group. Therefore, the rankings can produce meaningful weights, which can be applied to the observed data. Items could also be equally important (e.g. voice and bias suppression). The ultimate outcome from the weighting is that items that were deemed as more important by users will receive higher importance in the composite index of the costs and the quality of access to justice. 1. Challenges There are several serious disadvantages in the use of stated preferences to weight items of the quality of the procedure and the quality of the outcome indicators26. Like the item scores, the ranking of the items have to be estimated empirically. One option is to calculate the items and their relative importance from the same sample of users of justice, meaning that the same questionnaire will collect two types of data. 25 For details on the research design and the methodology of data collection see Appendix 1 26 See supra III.B.3 16 Alternatively, the item scores could be estimated from one sample of users, while the importance is estimated from a different sample. Deriving stated preferences from the same or different sample inevitably increases the cost of the indexing construction. Furthermore, in the latter option, there is the risk of the two populations differing in some known or unknown manner. The comparability of the paths to justice could also be an issue. Another challenge may be the moment that stated preferences are a valid and reliable reflection of what users of justice find important, as this could change with time. Change in legislation or external factors might influence the perceptions regarding the relative importance of the items of the quality of the procedure and the quality of the outcome indicators. B. Association weights extracted with factor analysis In this section, we focus on the parsimony function of factor analysis and its ability to produce meaningful weights of the items that measure the quality of the procedure and the quality of outcome of paths to justice. Factor analysis (FA) is a statistical procedure for data reduction and identification of latent factors in the data. Thompson adds two additional intentions of the FA – evaluation of score validity and development of theory regarding the construct27. There are numerous methods for factor extraction which attempt to achieve the goals of FA from different perspectives. For the purpose of this example, we will use the method of principal component analysis (PCA). The advantage of PCA is its ability to analyze the total variance in the correlation matrix to reduce the data structure. Unlike the alternative methods for extraction of common factors, PCA operates with components extracted from the correlation matrix, and not with hypothetical factors28. Another advantage of PCA is that it extracts components from the total variance, whereas the other methods use only the common variance between items. Unlike most of the parametric statistical procedures, FA does not assume normal distribution of the data. Two assumptions underlie FA. First, it is applicable to continuous variables. Most items in the MA2J measurement instrument use a 5 point Likert scale or are re-scaled to a 5 point scale29, meaning we can apply FA. Second, the variables must be linearly related to each other. This assumption could be checked through investigation of the co-relation matrix or review of the scatter matrix. The primary goal of PCA is to reduce a set of correlated items into a few components which are more amenable to interpretation. In the context of the MA2J methodology, the components are expected to be indicators and sub-indicators of the costs and quality of the paths to justice, and the items are the individual questions from the measurement instruments. For instance, PCA could indicate whether the five variables designed to measure the procedural justice primarily measure this factor, or if the data captures other facets of the experience with the procedure. After estimating the number of components, PCA reveals the association between each variable and the extracted component. These correlations could be interpreted as the fit between an 27 BRUCE THOMPSON, Exploratory and confirmatory factor analysis : understanding concepts and applications pp. 4-5 (American Psychological Association 1st ed. 2004). 28 PAUL KLINE, An easy guide to factor analysis (Routledge. 1994). 29 The costs are measured at ordinal level and then re-scaled again to ordinal variables. 17 item and a component. Items with high correlations are deemed to be good measures of the component. On the other hand, items with low correlations measure some other factors, which are not shared with the other items. The measure of the association between the individual items and the measured indicators could be used as weights when interpreting the results from the MA2J studies. Items better related to the particular indicator will be given more weight in the index variable. Later, we discuss the capability of PCA to provide meaningful weights for the MA2J data. In FA, the measure of extracted communalities is directly related to the factor loadings. The communality of a variable reflects the amount of variance, explained by the extracted factors. If there is only one factor identified in the data structure, the communalities express the variance explained by this single factor. There is a direct relationship between the factor loadings and the communalities - the latter are the sum of the squares of the factor loadings. The application of the communalities or the factor loadings as weights will reward the variables, which are closely associated with the indicator. A practical question is which measure to use as weight for the observed variables – the communalities or the factor loadings. As the former are a product of the latter, both weights will produce similar, but not equal, results. In order to avoid further complications of the interpretation of the weighted variables, we recommend the use of the factor loadings as weights for the observed data. 1. Challenges The factor loadings can be used as meaningful weights if there is only one factor extracted. There is the possibility that despite the careful alignment of the measurement instrument with the theoretical framework, the variables in fact measure two or more factors. In this case, the communalities will be the product of more than one factor loading. While this will contradict our theoretical framework, it will also challenge the use of the factor loadings as weights. If the data does not fit the theoretical model well, the validity of the measurement instrument has to be carefully scrutinized. Another practical challenge is the sample size. Although there is no fixed requirement for the size of the sample, there are certain suggestions. The general advice is that larger samples will allow for more valid and reliable weights extraction. C. Association weights extracted with multiple regression Multiple regression is the second statistical procedure that will be reviewed for the purpose of deriving association weights. Briefly stated, standard multiple regression allows for the assessment of the relationship between one continuous dependent variable and numerous independent variables. For example, is satisfaction with the criminal justice system related to several independent variables, such as respectful treatment, participation, being informed and/or sentence severity? Using multiple regression allows for the identification of a set of predictor variables that, when combined, will provide a useful estimate of the score of the participant’s criterion variable. It is possible to predict the score of the dependent variable based on 18 the scores of several variables. Multiple regression accounts for the variance in the observed scores. The regression equation is as follows: εββββ +++++= kk XXXy ...22110 Where Y is the predicted or explained value on the dependent variable, X represents the independent variables explaining the variance on Y, and B is the coefficient assigned to each independent variables. These coefficients are the weights attributed to each independent variable and are similar to the factor loadings in FA. Finally, A is the intercept30. To find out which variables in the model contribute to the prediction of the dependent variable and to what extent, the beta coefficient is used. Since this research is solely weighting the procedure and outcome – elements which do no need standardization as they are on the same scale – conversion is not necessary and the un-standardized coefficient can be utilized. Applied to the current research, the weighted equation for procedural justice would be as follows: Y(composite procedural) = A + b1 (process control) + b2 (decision control) + b3 (consistency) + b (bias suppression) + b (accuracy) + b (correctability) +b (ethicality) 1. Challenges An issue with multi collinearity arises if two or more independent variables are highly correlated with one another, and, therefore would basically be measuring the same phenomenon. This study will utilize the value .75 as a threshold for identifying multi collinearity. Different methods are available to ensure that this limitation does not exist. This analysis will follow the rule that regression with one independent variable requires 30 observations, and each additional independent variable added to the equation will require an additional 10 observations. If measuring procedural justice, which is calculated using 7 independent variables, a minimum of 90 observations would be necessary. As seen in Figure 2, there will be a largely skewed value for each variable if multiple regression is used. One possibility is to leave the non significant variables out of the equation. The existence of non-significant values is another issue suggesting multiple regression is an inferior method when compared to FA. Because of the distorted weighted values derived by multiple regression, FA may prove to be the superior method in extracting weights for this research. The other option is to assume that variables 1 and 2 are the primary predictor variables affecting the criterion variable of satisfaction with the procedure. As they are the only variables which are statistically significant, the rest may be eliminated. Multiple regression is furthermore an inferior method due to its need to meet the above mentioned assumptions – in addition to other statistical issues such as normality, linearity and independence of errors – which is often a difficult task. 30 BARBARA G. TABACHNICK & LINDA S. FIDELL, Using multivariate statistics (Allyn and Bacon 4th ed. 2001). 19 D. Using un- weighted data The possibility of using an un-weighted index should not be overlooked. Often, index systems rely on equal weighting. In this case, the means will simply be utilized in an equation as follows: Y(composite procedural) = (1)voice + (1)decision control + (1)consistency + (1)bias suppression + (1)accuracy + (1)correctability + (1)ethicality Comparing weighted and un-weighted indexes will often yield similar results. This outcome leaves one to question whether a weighted index will be necessary to measure the quality of a path to justice. Weighted and un-weighted scores will be highly correlated, as was the case in Likert’s classic study measuring attitudes which found a .99 correlation31. Additionally, Nunnally argues that it is difficult to defend any given method as superior to simply summing un-weighted ratings32. As discussed above, many legal indexes do not apply any weights to the observed data. Several issues emerge when weighting the observed data. The assumptions required when conducting statistical analyses were discussed above. As is the case of the stated preferences, which was described using the law student experiment, applying one type of weight to a given criteria cannot be generalized to all types of legal problems. Other methods, such as the multiple regression, produce difficult to interpret weights which cannot be applied without additional transformation. It is also possible that the data severely contradicts the theoretical model which could render the weights meaningless. Finally, there is inevitable discrepancy between the weights derived with statistical methods and the actual preferences among the population of users of specific path to justice. V. Application of weights In this section, we apply the extracted weights to the observed data and analyze the impact of the weights. A good weight is expected to draw the observed data closer to the real properties of the studied phenomena. When the units of measurement are perceptions about the quality of the procedures and the outcomes, it is difficult to find precise benchmarks to assess the performance of the weights. In order to study the performance of the three weighting schemes, we are going to compare the weighted data with the observed data. Following the discussion above, three types of weights were extracted from two data sets (see Table 2). According to our taxonomy, the factor analysis (FA) weights and the multiple regression (MR) weights are extracted association weights. The third weighting model (Stated Preferences – SP) is based on users’ stated preferences (see 31 RENSIS LIKERT, A method of constructing an attitude scale, in Scaling: A sourcebook for Behavioral Scientists, (G. Maranell ed., 1974). 32 JUM C. NUNNALLY, Psychometric theory (McGraw-Hill 2d ed. 1978). 20 Appendix A for details on the computation of the indexes). Both association weights were extracted from a sample of users of justice who attempted to solve a consumption dispute. Data from a quasi-experiment with law students was used to compute the stated preferences weights. Despite the fact that the weights were taken from different samples and different legal problems, there is a significant positive correlation between the FA and the SP33 weights. Positive correlation as high as .79, for example, suggests that the difference between the association and the importance weights lies mainly in the extraction method. The positive sign of the correlation indicates that the items which measure better higher-level concept are also rated as more important. Extended further, the finding can be translated into a hypothesis which states that the users’ perceptions about paths to justice reflect both the actual experiences and the importance of the indicators used. Although extracted from the same data set, the correlation between the FA and MR weights is lower than the association between the FA and SP weights34. Least correlated are the MR and the SP weights35. This is a surprising finding, given the high association between the FA and SP. Looking at the MR weights, it is apparent that the method produces somewhat difficult to interpret weights, which cannot be used without significant transformations (see Table 2: Weights). The discrepancy is a signal to critically scrutinize the potential of the multiple regression analysis, thus providing meaningful weights in the context of measuring access to justice. Table 2: Weights Indicator Association weights - FA Association weights -MR Stated preferences weights Decision control 0.81 0.37 0.86 Correctability 0.84 0.14 1.09 Bias Suppression 0.89 0.44 1.22 Process Control 0.76 0.04 0.99 Ethicality 0.77 0.05 0.85 Consistency 0.82 0.04 1.04 Accuracy 0.84 0.05 1.20 Figure 2 reveals the results from the application of the three different weights to the actual data. Visibly, the MR weighed data significantly deviate from the raw scores and the other two weighting options. The transformation is not only in the item scales, 33 r=.79 34 r=.60 35 r=.13 21 but also in the relationships between the items. More consistency is significantly observed between the observed data and data weighted with the FA and the SP methods. When analyzing the relative position of the seven items, we find a negative correlation36 between the observed data and the MR weighted data. Not only does the multiple regression method produce difficult to interpret results, but this method also significantly affects the ranks of the observed items. Figure 2: Weighted data 0 1 2 3 4 Ac cu ra cy Co rre cta bil ity Et hic ali ty Pr oc es s C on tro l De cis ion co nt ro l Co ns ist en cy Bi as S up pr es sio n Raw score FA MR SP On the other hand, the FA and the SP methods change the order of the items to a much lesser degree in the observed data. The SP weighted data has a somewhat higher level of correlation with the observed data37 than the FA method38 does. Both correlations have similar strengths, and it could be concluded that the two methods produce comparable results. Another argument for the hypothesis that the association and the importance weights measure the same phenomena but with different approaches is the high correlation between the ranks of the items weighted with the two schemes39. The result of comparison between three models for extraction of weights suggests that the FA procedure has the most potential for generation of informative weights. Both theoretical and practical arguments imply the suitability of FA. First, the weights extracted from FA have intuitive meaning without any transformation. They represent the relationship of the item to the higher-order concept. Therefore, the weighting denotes that the items which are better related to the unobservable indicator will receive higher weights. From a practical point of view, the FA weights also have certain advantages. The weights could be extracted from the existing data without the need to ask the same sample of respondents new questions or to compute the weights from a different sample. 36 r=-.58 37 r=.57 38 r=.43 39 r=.96 22 Another major advantage of the FA weighting model is that it could be applied at higher levels in the Access to Justice Index. For instance, after extraction of the weights of the individual items, FA could be used to discover the weights of the sub- indicators into the indicators. In the next step, FA could be used to explore the weights of the three indicators before they are aggregated into a composite index. Many of the advantages of the FA weights are inherent to the SP weights. Their most important benefit is the clear logic behind the stated preferences on the importance of the weights. An apparent disadvantage is the practical difficulties related to the collection of additional data that the method requires. As the analysis in the preceding paragraphs shows, after weighting with the FA and the SP weights, the data do not change dramatically. This could be an argument that the FA weights are a more efficient mean of weighting the observed data. Weighting observed data could improve the validity, but only if the weights indeed adjust the data in the right direction. However, when certain requirements regarding the weights are not met, a non-weighted index will be superior to a weighted index. First, proper data must be obtained via a sufficiently large sample size. Second, regarding FA, the data could reveal negative factor loadings, which would cause a problem when applying and interpreting the weights to the data. Issues may also arise when the data do not meet expectations. An example would be the discovery of a multi-factor construct when the theory or the expectations suggest only one factor. In either of these two situations, the data should remain non-weighted. When one or more of these concepts is lacking, it has been suggested to refrain from using weights, as Nunnally has asserted that this option is often the best choice40. VI. Index validation Once a composite index has been formulated to measure ‘access to justice,’ it is beneficial to validate the index, or, more specifically, focusing on external validation. External validation tests the validity of the index by examining the correlation of the final value and some other indicator of the variable under study. The current research uses the indicators discussed above to calculate the quality of the procedure (procedural justice, informational justice, interpersonal justice, and restorative justice) and the quality of the outcome (distributive justice, corrective justice, restorative justice, retributive justice, informational justice, utilitarianism, transformative justice, legal pragmatism, and formal justice). One can hypothesize that these indicators are measuring quality, or perceptions of satisfaction, with the procedure. As a result, the item that measures user satisfaction can serve as a presumed indicator measuring the same variable of quality of the procedure and quality of the outcome. This index validation presupposes that those users who score a given path with a high rating are likely to state that they are satisfied with the procedure. Therefore, when scores are equivalent for this item and the index score overall, conclusions can be made regarding the accuracy of the survey. Specifically, it measures what it is supposed to measure. To briefly illustrate index validation of the Access to Justice Index, we will take the sub-index score of the quality of the procedure in the data 40 NUNNALLY supra note 32. 23 from the consumer dispute commission study in the Netherlands, and examine its relation to the item measuring satisfaction with the procedure. Table 3: Correlations Of Satisfaction With Non-Weighted Scores And Weighted Scores Sub-indicator Weighted Score using FA Non-Weighted Score Procedural Justice .846** .844** Interpersonal Justice .669** .635** Informational Justice .645** .646** **. Correlation is significant at the .01 level (2-tailed). The data conclude that while the difference is marginal, the weighted scores more accurately depict a valid index, assuming that satisfaction serves as a reasonable proxy variable. The question that does arise is whether this data is more in support of the non-weighting option, as the differences seem insignificant (i.e. .846 vs. .844). More importantly, however, is the strong correlation between the weighted scores and satisfaction, therefore suggesting the index is a valid measure of the quality of the procedure. VII. Conclusion The study and comparison of the cost and quality of paths to justice could be significantly facilitated by construction of composite index. On their ways to justice, the users evaluate distinct properties of the process. According to our theoretical framework, the three most important indicators are the costs, the quality of the procedure, and the quality of the outcome. These concepts were operationalized in detail in related articles and briefly outlined above. Operationalization of the indicators, however, is only the first step in index construction. It is equally important to put in place a transparent and coherent scheme for rating the importance of the indicators. This scheme should be operationalized at the three levels at which indicators are aggregated. Establishing criteria for prioritizing the indicators is one of the most important phases of the index construction. Giving inappropriate weights to the indicators could tilt the composite index into a direction that compromises the validity and integrity of the measurement effort. The importance of the indicators is expressed through the process of weighting. Not all observed indicators require re-assessment of their importance. Some indicators reflect factual statements, which could be true or false, but cannot be more important or less important. Other indicators, such as the quality of the procedure and the quality of the outcome, are subjective, meaning that two users of justice could assess similar experiences differently. Both assessments could be true, depending on the subjective value a person places on a particular indicator. It is completely possible that one user of justice values the opportunity to have her voice heard more than the possibility to correct wrong information. Another pair of users could disagree on what is more important in the outcome – its restorative effect or its enforceability. Based on the 24 subjective preferences, both users could be right. Apparently, the subjective preferences could have a strong influence on the composite index. If the preferences could be identified and the structure is stable, the observed data could be adjusted accordingly or, as otherwise said, weighted. In the paper above, we discuss two models of weighting – stated preferences and extracted association weights. Despite the significant difference in the perspectives from which the two models extract the weights, we saw that when applied to empirical data both models produce very similar outcomes. Findings like this suggest that users of justice might have stable preferences with regard to the importance of the subjective indicators. However, we tested this hypothesis only with the quality of the procedure indicators. More research on other paths to justice is needed in order to formulate more conclusive inferences on whether there are universal, or at least path- specific, preference structures. If both methods for weighting produce similar results, which one should be recommended? Before answering this question, we should consider the alternative of not using weights. Above, we discuss numerous disadvantages of the application of the weights. At least three groups of arguments against weighting and in favour of using the observed data could be outlined. First is the validity argument – weighting could adjust the data, but, at the same time, jeopardize its validity. In most studies, these risks will be difficult to control against, since there is often no base-line data to assess the performance of the index. Next, the practical argument that extraction of weights requires additional resources appears. This is particularly true for the importance weights. In the end, the application of weights should be critically reviewed against their impact on the data validity. In the text above, we outline a strategy for testing the validity of the weights against concepts, which could serve as proxies of the indicators (i.e. perceptions on satisfaction or favourability). What was said in the preceding paragraph does not necessarily mean that weighting is harmful for the validity of composite index. It is a caution that only weights, based on solid data and sound theoretical models, should be used to adjust the observed data. If this is the case, we recommend the use of factor analysis for extraction of association weights. The model is based on the expectation that the lower-level items measure the unobserved upper-level items. In general, the association weights are easier to extract than the importance weights. In addition, our empirical data strongly suggests that the association weights extracted with factor analysis produce similar results to the importance weights. With this analysis, the methodology for the Access to Justice Index has been reviewed and substantiated. The framework of the measurement has been outlined and the use of indexes was examined. The construction now allows for future evaluation on different legal paths a user encounters. As a result, not only can comparisons be made to provide the user with his or her best option, but improvements can be made where values depict an unsatisfactory picture. An accurately computed index is more likely to result by following the structure above and, subsequently, a greater understanding of the quality of justice will evolve. 25 Appendix A: Methodology for data collection 1. Data used for the extraction of association weights Empirical data on experiences of users of justice in the Netherlands were collected through a cross-sectional survey in 2008. The study collects responses from individuals who experienced a vehicle-related consumer problem and sought resolution through the Dutch Consumer Dispute Commission. All individuals who addressed the Commission with vehicle-related problems in the previous 12 months received an invitation for participation in this study via the Consumer Dispute Commission. In this invitation letter, they were told that the purpose of the study was to assess their experience with the Consumer Dispute Commission concerning the cost and quality of the procedure and the outcome they obtained. The people who were invited were offered a monetary reward of � 25 for their participation. In total, 850 individuals were invited to participate in the study. 230 of them responded to the invitation, resulting in a response rate of 27.1%. 34 of them were invited to participate in a focus group study. In addition, 74 respondents were asked to participate in the study at a later point in time, as it was decided to conduct a second survey with an improved version of the questionnaire. In total, 151 usable responses were collected. 2. Data used for the extraction of importance weights In order to understand the users’ preferences on the items of the quality of the outcome and quality of the procedure indicators, a quasi-experiment was carried out. 130 second-year law students from Tilburg University were invited to complete an online questionnaire that measured how the individual items are ranked against similar items41. For instance, the respondents were asked to rank the accuracy of the procedure against all 6 other indicators that measure procedural justice. In this group, the respondents had to rank the items from 1 to 7, with 1 representing the most important item and 8 representing the least important. According to our theoretical framework, two or more indicators could carry equal levels of importance. Therefore, the questionnaire allowed placing the same ranks on more than one item. Hypothetically, a respondent could have chosen to rank all indicators as 1, which would have meant that they share equal levels of importance. Four different types of the survey were distributed to groups of similar sizes. Each group was presented with a dispute case and its resolution, to which the students had to relate their responses42. The four cases had different underlying problems: − Armed robbery; 41 All law students enrolled in a course English Legal Language Skills were invited to participate. The questionnaire was distributed in English which might account for certain degree of measurement error. 42 For the texts of the four case studies see http://www.measuringaccesstojustice.com/index.php/ELLS 26 − Relationship breakdown and split-up; − Denial of student loan; − Consumer problem with service provider. In total, 102 valid responses were received, equivalent to a response rate of 78%. Particular reliability risks for the data collected through internet questionnaires were the two response order effects – primacy and yea-saying . In order to identify patterns in the data which signal those effects, we counted how many times a respondent selected identical values for two adjacent indicators. There are 33 indicators in the sample, grouped into 7 categories43. The mean value of the repeated scores is 8.11, with standard deviation of 5.95. A cut off value of 1.96 standard deviations above the mean44 was selected for removing responses as plagued by primacy and/or yea- saying. Following this procedure, 4 responses were eliminated from the data set,45 resulting in 98 total responses. 43 3 categories of indicators of the quality of the procedure, 3 categories of indicators of the quality of the outcome and 1 group which asks for the importance of the 3 general indicators – costs of the procedure, quality of the procedure and quality of the outcome. 44 Cut off value = 19.77 20≈ repeated rankings out of the 33 responses 45 Additionally, the data set was analyzed for inconsistency in the ratings. The major concern was that for some set of indicators, non-consequential ranks were observed – i.e. item rated at 7th place but no item rated 6th. As this inconsistency would contradict the logic of the ranking, we re-organized the interrupted ranks into non-interrupted series. This transformation slightly decreased the mean ratings and improved the consistency of the data. 27 Appendix B: Computation of weights 1. Association weights – principal components analysis Table 4 reports the component loadings of the 7 items measuring the procedural justice concept. Only one component exceeds the eigenvalues threshold, indicating that the common variation is associated with one component. The component loadings are subsequently used as weights. Table 4: Association weights – principal component analysis Indicator Component Loading Accuracy 0.84 Correctability 0.84 Ethicality 0.77 Process Control 0.76 Decision control 0.81 Consistency 0.82 Bias Suppression 0.89 2. Association weights - multiple regression analysis Table 4 shows the un-standardized β coefficients from the multiple regression of the 7 items that measure the procedural justice on the satisfaction with the procedure. The β coefficients were used as weights without additional conversion. Table 5: Association weights - multiple regression analysis Indicator MR Accuracy 0.05 Correctability 0.14 Ethicality 0.05 Process Control 0.04 Decision control 0.37** Consistency 0.04 Bias Suppression 0.44** **The coefficient is statistically significant at the 0.01 level 3. Importance weights Unlike the association weights, the importance weights were obtained from a quasi- experiment with a sample of law students. The respondents were asked to report how important the particular indicator is with regard to a hypothetical dispute. Each indicator is ranked from 1 (most important) to n (least important, where n = the number of indicators). Therefore, lower ranks signified more important indicators. In 28 order to transform the ranks into weights, we first reversed the order of the indicator. From each score we extracted its deviation from the mean. The sign of the mean deviation was then reversed and again added to the mean. We take the natural logarithm of the reversed score as weight (see Table 6). Table 6: Importance weights Original value Reversed value Natural logarithm Accuracy 2.37 3.32 1.20 Correctability 2.71 2.98 1.09 Ethicity 3.35 2.34 0.85 Process control 3.00 2.69 0.99 Decision control 3.32 2.37 0.86 Consistency 2.88 2.82 1.04 Bias suppression 2.30 3.39 1.22 work_2fjwwisssvg35n4sfsyy55jaem ---- A Taxonomy of Organizational Justice Theories ? Academy of Management Review, 1987, Vol. 12, No. 1, 9-22. A Taxonomy of Organizational Justice Theories JERALD GREENBERG Ohio State University A taxonomy is presented that categorizes theories of organizational justice with respect to two independent dimensions: a reactive- proactive dimension and a process-content dimension. Various theo- ries within each of the four resulting categories are identified. The implications of the taxonomy are discussed with respect to clarifying theoretical interrelationships, tracking research trends, and identify- ing needed areas of research. Stimulated by conceptualizations of justice in organizations by such theorists as Homans (1961), Adams (1965), and Walster, Berscheid, and Wal- ster (1973), organizational researchers devoted considerable attention in the 1960s and 1970s to testing propositions about the distribution of pay- ment and other work-related rewards derived from equity theory (for reviews, see Campbell & Pritchard, 1976; Greenberg, 1982). Although reviews and critiques of equity theory once domi- nated the pages of organizational journals (e.g., Goodman & Friedman, 1971; Pritchard, 1969; Weick, 1966), more recently it has been the sub- ject of far less attention (Reis, 1986). It would be a mistake, however, to view this trend as an indication that organizational scientists are less interested in matters of justice and fairness in organizations than they used to be. Indeed, con- cerns about fairness have been expressed in such organizational domains as conflict resolution (Aram & Salipante, 1981), personnel selection (Arvey, 1979), labor disputes (Walton & McKersie, 1965), and wage negotiation (Mahoney, 1975), to name just a few. Although research inspired by equity theory has slowed down greatly, there have emerged a variety of different approaches to justice that are at least as useful in explaining behavior in a broader variety of organizational contexts. Because there has been a proliferation of such newer approaches and because these may be less familiar to organizational scientists, the present paper will categorize various con- ceptualizations of justice around a taxonomic scheme. This taxonomy will not only offer a par- simonious way of organizing these various con- ceptualizations, but in so doing, will highlight their interrelationships and their importance to the study of organizations. Dimensions of the Taxonomy The present taxonomy is derived by combin- ing two conceptually independent dimensions: a reactive-proactive dimension and a process- content dimension. It is not assumed that these are the only organizing dimensions that may be identified. Indeed, it is possible that different tax- onomic schemes may be proposed that are based on completely different conceptual dimensions. However, the dimensions identified in the pres- ent taxonomy appear to be very useful ones for organizing a wide range of conceptualizations of interest in the field of organizational behavior. Reactive-Proactive Dimension The reactive-proactive dimension was sug- gested by a distinction made by Van Avermaet, McClintock, and Moskowitz (1978), and was used 9 to organize the equity theory literature by Green- berg (1982). The distinction is between seeking to redress injustice and striving to attain justice. A reactive theory of justice focuses on people's attempts either to escape from or to avoid per- ceived unfair states. Such theories examine reac- tions to injustices. By contrast, proactive theories focus on behaviors designed to promote justice. They examine behaviors attempting to create just states. Process-Content Dimension The second dimension, the process-content dimension, was inspired by legal research dis- tinguishing between the way verdicts are derived and what those verdicts are (Walker, Lind, & Thibaut, 1979). Mahoney (1983) made a similar distinction by differentiating between the pro- cesses by which wages are determined and the outcome of those processes. As such, we may distinguish between approaches to justice that focus on the ends achieved and the means used to acquire those ends. A process approach to justice focuses on how various outcomes (in organizations, pay and rec- ognition are good examples) are determined. Such orientations focus on the fairness of the pro- cedures used to make organizational decisions and to implement those decisions. In contrast, content approaches concern themselves with the fairness of the resulting distribution of outcomes. These perspectives address the relative fairness of the outcomes received by various organiza- tional units (typically either individuals or groups). Identifying Theories Within the Taxonomy It is assumed that the reactive-proactive dimen- sion and the process-content dimension are inde- pendent of each other, thereby yielding four dis- tinct classes of justice conceptualizations when the two dimensions are combined. Table 1 organ- izes these approaches and identifies a primary exemplar of each. Two points must be made regarding the theo- ries in this taxonomy. First, no attempt has been made to be exhaustive. Instead, the theories iden- tified and described are ones that are either well- established or promising ones within psychol- ogy or sociology, fields within which the study of justice in organizations traditionally has been rooted. Limiting the examples does not imply that other theories would not fit in. Rather, in view of the clarifying function of the present work, ex- cluding them is more reflective of a judgment regarding the limitations of their demonstrated or potential value for organizational study. Second, although some of the theories classi- fied by the present taxonomy have been widely applied to organizational contexts, none were formulated with organizations in mind as their exclusive focus. Even Adams's (1965) popular the- ory of inequity, originally tested in work settings, has been described as a general theory of social behavior (Walster et al., 1973). Other theories presented here originated within the legal milieu (e.g., Thibaut & Walker, 1975). Nonetheless, because the theories have been, or are now being used to explain organizational behavior, they will be referred to collectively as theories of organizational justice. Table 1 Taxonomy of Organizational Justice Theories with Corresponding Predominant Exemplars Reactive- Content-Process Dimension Proactive Dimension Content Process Reactive Content Reactive Process Reactive Equity theory Procedural justice (Adams, 1965) theory (Thibaut & Walker, 1975) Proactive Content Proactive Process Proactive Justice judgment Allocation preference theory (Leventhal theory (Leventhal, (1976a, 1980) Karuza, & Fry, 1980) 10 Reactive Content Theories Reactive content theories are conceptual ap- proaches to justice that focus on how individuals respond to unfair treatment. Organizational sci- entists are probably most familiar with this class of justice theory because most popular conceptu- alizations of justice in organizations fall within this category. Included among these theories are Homans's (1961) theory of distributive justice, and Adams's (1965) and Walster et al.'s (1973) ver- sions of equity theory (see also Walster, Walster, & Berscheid, 1978). Despite several differences in the specifics of their formulation (see Cohen & Greenberg, 1982), these theories share an impor- tant common orientation in explicitly stating that people will respond to unfair relationships by displaying certain negative emotions, which they will be motivated to escape by acting so as to redress the experienced inequity. It is this aspect of the theories that qualifies them as reactive content theories: They focus on how people react to unfair distributions of rewards and resources. Conceptually rooted in the tradition of balance theories popular in the 1950s and 1960s (e.g., Festinger, 1957; Heider, 1958) these approaches to justice conceptualized "equitable," or "distri- butively just" relations as ones in which there was an equal balance between the ratio of a person's contributions and his or her outcomes. Unequal balances, such as those that existed whenever workers were either overpaid or un- derpaid relative to another person with equal contributions, were assumed to be unpleasant, which were theorized to prompt changes in job satisfaction and/or performance. In particular, Adams's (1965) theory of inequity, the approach that inspired most of the justice-related research in organizational settings, specified that over- paid workers would feel "guilty" and that under- paid workers would feel "angry." These nega- tive states were expected to motivate behavioral and/or attitudinal changes on the part of the workers involved that altered, either behavior- ally or perceptually, the relationship between their own and another's contributions and out- comes (cf., Greenberg, 1984). For example, work- ers perceiving an inequitable state may react behaviorally by altering their performance levels, and/or cognitively by attempting to justify the outcomes received (Walster et al., 1978). It was, no doubt, because the theoretical met- rics were so explicitly suited to work-related exchanges that equity theory became so popu- larly applied to organizational research. Indeed, it was within simulated work settings that most of the research on equity theory was conducted (e.g., Lawler & O'Gara, 1967; Pritchard, Dun- nette, & Jorgenson, 1972). In the prototypical test of equity theory, the experimenter manipulated inequity by leading worker-subjects to believe that the basis for their payment was unfair- thereby creating either "underpayment inequity" or "overpayment inequity." For example, this may have included: (a) leading subjects to be- lieve that an error occurred that caused them to receive the same wage as their more qualified co-workers, thereby manipulating overpayment (e.g., Adams & Rosenbaum, 1962), or (b) allow- ing subjects to discover through conversations with co-workers that they were equally qualified but unequally paid (e.g., Garland, 1973). Typically, performance on some work task- popularly a proofreading task for which quan- tity and quality measures could be taken-con- stituted the dependent variable. According to equity theory, underpaid workers should be less productive and less satisfied than equitably paid workers and overpaid workers should be more productive and less satisfied than equitably paid workers. In general, and over a wide variety of experimental settings, support was found for these predictions (for a review, see Greenberg, 1982). Several sociological theories that have devel- oped in response to certain aspects of Adams's conceptualization, particularly the nature of social comparisons, also should be included within the category of reactive content theories. Among these is the status value version of equity theory proposed by Berger and his associates (Anderson, Berger, Zelditch, & Cohen, 1969; Berger, Zelditch, Anderson, & Cohen, 1972). 11 According to this formulation, a person's feel- ings of inequity and reactions to inequity result not from comparisons made to a specific other person (referred to as a "local comparison"), but from comparisons to a generalized other (referred to as a "referential comparison"), such as an occupational group. Extending this approach, Jasso's (1980) theory of distributive justice ignored the outside comparisons in justice evaluations altogether, and defined justice in terms of the comparisons people make between their actual share of goods and their beliefs about a "just share." Despite some important conceptual dif- ferences between these theories and the more familiar Adams formulation, their similar focus on how people react to beliefs about the unfair distribution of outcomes (regardless of the com- parative basis on which these judgments are formed) allows these theories to be clearly cate- gorized as reactive content theories. More closely related to traditional equity theory, and the final reactive content theory of justice to be identified, is the theory of relative deprivation (Crosby, 1976). Based on findings dat- ing back to World War II (Stouffer, Suchman, DeVinney, Star, & Williams, 1949), but also more recently examined in organizational contexts (Crosby, 1984; Martin, 1981), the relative depriva- tion orientation to justice is becoming increas- ingly more popular among organizational scien- tists. In its most general form, the relative depri- vation approach asserts that certain reward dis- tribution patterns will encourage people to make certain social comparisons, which will lead to feelings of deprivation and resentment, causing a variety of reactions ranging from depression through the outbreak of violent riots (Martin, 1981). The term "relative deprivation," first used by Stouffer et al. (1949), refers to the counterintuitive finding that black soldiers stationed in the south felt more satisfied with military life than black soldiers stationed in northern bases despite socio- economic conditions being more favorable in the north. These effects were attributed to the ten- dency for black soldiers in the south to feel more privileged than their civilian counterparts in the south, whereas, black soldiers in the north felt relatively less privileged than their civilian coun- terparts in the north. Although most of the subse- quent relative deprivation research focused on violent attempts to change political systems (Crosby, 1976), some efforts have focused on how aggrieved employees react to organizationally induced discontent (Martin, 1981). For example, large-scale survey studies by Crosby (1982, 1984) found that working women, especially those in high prestige jobs, who although they may be more advantaged than nonworking women, tend to be more aggrieved because they compare themselves to working men, relative to whom they are less advantaged. Research of this type is typical of that generated today by relative deprivation theory. Because it examines how people will respond to perceived unfair reward distributions, relative deprivation theory clearly can be identified as a reactive content theory. Proactive Content Theories In contrast to reactive content theories, which focus on how workers respond to fair and unfair outcome distributions, proactive content theories focus on how workers attempt to create fair out- come distributions. The major theoretical state- ments in this category have come from Leventhal (1976a, 1980), who in the late 1960s and early 1970s conducted a series of laboratory studies in which the basic pattern of independent and dependent variables found in traditional reac- tive accounts of justice were reversed. That is, Leventhal and his associates typically manipu- lated concerns about justice (through appropri- ate instructional sets) to examine their impact on reward allocation decisions (for reviews, see Freedman & Montanari, 1980; Mikula, 1980). Leventhal (1976b) contended that people some- times proactively strive to create equitable distri- butions of reward-those in which the rewards received are proportional to the contributions made-because these will be the most benefi- cial to all concerned parties in the long run. Indeed, many studies (e.g., Greenberg & Leven- thal, 1976; Leventhal & Michaels, 1969) have shown that allocators often divide resources equi- tablv between recipients (for reviews, see Adams 12 & Freedman, 1976; Freedman & Montanari, 1980). However, additional research has shown that allocators of rewards sometimes distribute those rewards in ways that violate the equity norm-such as by distributing rewards equally, or in accordance with recipients' needs (Schwin- ger, 1980). Recognizing that such violations of the equity norm may be completely fair under appropriate circumstances, Leventhal (1976a, 1980) formulated his justice judgment model. This model proposed that individuals attempt to make fair allocation decisions by variously applying several possible allocation rules to the situations they confront. For example, in situations in which the importance of maintaining social harmony between group members is stressed, the per- ceived fair allocation practice would call for fol- lowing the equality norm-dividing rewards equally regardless of possible differential contri- butions among recipients (Deutsch, 1975). Whereas Leventhal's approach to reward allo- cation practices is instrumental in character, another proactive content theory of justice, Ler- ner's (1977; Lerner & Whitehead, 1980) justice motive theory is decidedly more moralistic. Ler- ner (1982) argued that justice is the preeminent concern of human beings and the quest for jus- tice as a means to a profit-maximizing end (as Leventhal proposed) is a mythical illusion. Like Leventhal, however, Lerner recognized that allo- cation practices often go beyond the possibility of proportional equity. In fact, Lerner identified four principles that are commonly followed: (a) competition-allocations based on the outcome of performance, (b) parity-equal allocations, (c) equity- allocations based on relative contribu- tions, and (d) Marxian justice-allocations based on needs. Briefly, justice motive theory stipulates that the form of justice that will be followed in making allocation decisions will depend on the nature of the relations between the parties involved in con- junction with the focus of the parties on each other as individuals or as occupants of positions. For example, the theory predicts that an individ- ual reacting to a close friend as an individual will emphasize that person's needs when mak- ing an allocation decision. Similarly in more dis- tant relationships, people are expected to follow the parity norm when the other is recognized as an individual, and the equity norm when react- ing to the other as a role incumbent. Research relating various reward allocation practices to the nature of the relationship between people has been supportive of justice motive theory (e.g., Carles & Carver, 1979). Despite some differences in underlying philo- sophies, both justice judgment theory and jus- tice motive theory make similar predictions about how people will allocate rewards under various circumstances-predictions that largely have been supported by research (for a review, see Deutsch, 1985). Both of these approaches clearly qualify as proactive content theories of justice because they deal with how people seek to make decisions about the allocation of reward. Reactive Process Theories Although it appears that theories focusing on the fairness of the processes used to make deci- sions (process theories) do not differ appreciably from those theories focusing on the fairness of the resulting decisions (content theories), this is not the case because process theories stem from a different intellectual tradition-in particular, the law. In fact, legal scholars have commonly accepted that the procedures used to make judi- cial decisions will have a profound influence on the public's acceptance of them (Fuller, 1961). At approximately the same time when proac- tive content theories were formalized and re- searched (the early 1970s) a team of researchers at the University of North Carolina, John Thibaut and Laurens Walker, influenced by the tradition of research on legal procedures, undertook a series of investigations designed to compare reactions to various dispute resolution procedures (for a review, see Thibaut & Walker, 1975). Their theory of procedural justice distinguished be- tween three parties: two disputants (such as the litigants in a court case), and an intervening third party (such as a judge); and two stages of the dispute-resolution process: the process stage, during which evidence is presented, and the 13 decision stage, during which the evidence is used to resolve the dispute. The ability to control the selection and development of the evidence used to resolve the dispute is referred to as process control; the ability to determine the outcome of the dispute itself is referred to as decision control (Thibaut & Walker, 1978). The procedures used can vary regarding the degree of control the various parties have over each stage. In particular, procedures may be identified that give third parties control over: both outcomes and procedures, autocratic procedures; decisions but not processes, arbitration proce- dures; processes but not decisions, mediation procedures; and neither processes nor proce- dures, bargaining procedures. Finally, moot procedures are those in which the disputants and third parties share control over outcomes and processes. (Recently, Sheppard, 1984, has pro- posed a more extensive system.) Although reactions to all of these procedures were assessed, Thibaut and Walker were most interested in comparing autocratic and arbitra- tion procedures because these most closely dis- tinguished between the major legal systems. For example, the adversary system, used in Ameri- can and British courts, gives judges control over the verdict but leaves the process (e.g., selection of attorneys, presentation of evidence) in the hands of the disputants themselves. However, the inquisitorial system, used in continental Europe, gives judges control over the collection and presentation of evidence as well as the verdicts. The theory is concerned with how peo- ple will react to each of these decision-making procedures, thereby qualifying as a reactive pro- cess theory. The theory predicts that both liti- gants and observing disinterested parties will be more satisfied with procedures giving them process control (e.g., the adversary system) than those that do not (e.g., the inquisitorial system). The verdicts resulting from procedures offering process control are hypothesized to be perceived as fairer and to be better accepted than those resulting from procedures denying process con- trol. Many studies using a simulated legal deci- sion-making methodology (e.g., Lind, Kurtz, Musante, Walker, & Thibaut, 1980; Walker, Lind, & Thibaut, 1979) have supported this claim (for reviews, see Folger & Greenberg, 1985; Thibaut & Walker, 1975). Interestingly, procedures giv- ing diputants a voice in the decision-making pro- cess tend to enhance the acceptance of even unfavorable decisions (LaTour, 1978; Lind et al., 1980.) Other research has generalized the Thibaut and Walker findings to less formal settings. For example, Tyler and his associates found that reactions to encounters with police officers (Tyler & Folger, 1980), politicians, and teachers (Tyler & Caine, 1981) also are heavily influenced by the procedures that these authorities follow in treating their clients. Recently, organizational researchers have actively attempted to extend and apply Thibaut and Walker's theory of proce- dural justice to a variety of organizational con- texts, such as the resolution of labor disputes (Sheppard, 1984) and the appraisal of job perfor- mance (Greenberg, 1986a, 1986b), among oth- ers (for reviews, see Folger & Greenberg, 1985; Greenberg & Folger, 1983; Greenberg & Tyler, in press). Proactive Process Theories Of the theories identified in this taxonomy, probably the least well-known fall into the proac- tive process category. The predominant theoreti- cal position within this category is Leventhal, Karuza, and Fry's (1980) allocation preference theory. This is an outgrowth of Leventhal's (1976a, 1980) justice judgment model (described earlier) and is proposed as a general model of alloca- tion behavior. However, because the theory has been applied almost exclusively to procedural decisions rather than distributive ones (e.g., Fry & Cheney, 1981; Fry & Leventhal, 1979), it has operated as a proactive process theory. Thus, in contrast with the emphasis on dispute-resolution procedures typical of the reactive process theo- ries, the proactive process orientation tends to focus on allocation procedures. By using this orientation, one seeks to determine what proce- dures people will use to achieve justice. 14 Allocation preference theory asserts that allo- cation procedures will be preferred to the extent that they help the allocator attain valued goals, including the attainment of justice. In particular, the theory proposes that people hold expectan- cies that certain procedures will be differentially instrumental in meeting their goals, and that the procedure believed to be most likely to help attain one's goal will be the most preferred one. Eight procedures are identified that may help promote the attainment of justice. These include proce- dures that: (a) allow opportunities to select the decision-making agent, (b) follow consistent rules, (c) are based on accurate information, (d) identify the structure of decision-making power, (e) employ safeguards against bias, (f) allow for appeals to be heard, (g) provide opportunities for changes to be made in procedures, and (h) are based on prevailing moral and ethical stan- dards. The limited research inspired by allocation preference theory offers general support for it. The studies have been of two types-those in which the subjects respond to open-ended re- quests for examples of perceived fair or unfair procedures, and those in which subjects rate the importance of various allocation procedures manipulated in written scenarios. In one open- ended questionnaire study, Sheppard and Lewicki (in press) asked white-collar managers to identify unfair incidents across a variety of managerial roles. Among other principles, they found that subjects identified consistency, bias suppression, correctability, and ethicality, all principles of procedural justice proposed by Leventhal et al. (1980). Similarly, Greenberg (1 986a) asked middle managers to identify determinants of perceived fair performance evaluations, and found proce- dural determinants consistent with Leventhal et al.'s (1980) theory, namely: (a) the soliciting of workers' input prior to evaluations and using it as the basis of evaluations, (b) the availability of two-way communication during appraisal inter- views, (c) the opportunity to challenge/rebut the evaluation received, (d) the degree of the evalu- ator's familiarity with the ratee's work, and (e) the consistent application of evaluation stan- dards. Finally, in several role-playing investigations Fry (Fry & Cheney, 1981; Fry & Leventhal, 1979) found that consistency was believed to be the most important procedural determinant of fair- ness across a variety of allocation settings. In a more extensive study, Barrett-Howard and Tyler (1986) confirmed that consistency was a pow- erful determinant of perceived fairness across a wide variety of situations and social relationships. However, the other procedural elements identi- fied by Leventhal et al. (1980) were found to be perceived as differentially important as determi- nants of fairness in different types of social relationships. Implications of the Taxonomy The present taxonomy serves several useful functions. Among these are its ability: (a) to clar- ify conceptual interrelationships, (b) to track trends in organizational justice research, and (c) to identify needed areas of research and concep- tual development. Clarifying Conceptual Interrelationships Given the proliferation of research and theory about organizational justice, the present taxon- omy is a useful clarifier. By showing how the various theories are distinct and interrelated, the taxonomy provides a schema for conceptually organizing a growing body of work. One result of such a framework is reduced conceptual confusion. An important beneficial effect of this clarifying role is that it encourages researchers to be cogni- zant of existing conceptualizations and to apply the most useful ones to their own work. In the absence of such a taxonomy, it is too easy for researchers to use terms and apply concepts in ways that fail to incorporate existing precedents, thereby potentially adding confusion to the liter- ature. To illustrate this point, consider the recent pro- gram of research on "workplace justice" by Dal- ton and Todor (1 985a, 1985b). In several archival 15 studies, these researchers uncovered evidence that females were more preferentially treated than males in grievance-resolution settings. These findings of objective differences in outcome distributions were then taken as evidence of dif- ferences in "workplace justice outcomes." Al- though it is conceivable that these findings reflect perceived unfair states, it is not possible to con- clude from the Dalton and Todor data that sub- jective feelings of unfairness resulted from the objective outcomes identified. Because this was not their intent, and because they make no such claim, the investigators cannot be faulted. However, the point is that they are using the term "justice" in a way that is not in keeping with a voluminous literature that emphasizes jus- tice as a subjective state or quality. This is not to say that new, more objectively defined perspec- tives are without merit, but simply that current researchers on organizational justice should be aware of previous conceptual advances, such as those identified through the present taxonomy. Tracking Trends in Organizational Justice Research The present taxonomy identifies trends in the questions about justice posed in organizational research. A summary of the representative ques- tions asked by researchers developing the vari- ous types of theories and the corresponding dependent measures used appears in Table 2. Although there have been some recent investi- gations inspired by equity theory (e.g., Green- berg & Ornstein, 1983) and some conceptual clarifications (e.g., Cosier & Dalton, 1983), it is clear that interest in reactive content approaches has waned (Reis, 1986). Instead the emphasis has been on more proactive and more process- oriented conceptualizations. In essence, then, two shifts are identified-a shift from reactive to proactive theories and a shift from content to pro- cess theories. In reaction to the reactive approach of Adams's work in the 1960s (e.g., Adams & Rosenbaum, 1962) investigators such as Leventhal (Leventhal & Michaels, 1969) and Messe (1971) pioneered a more proactive approach in the late 1960s and early 1970s. With this, there was a shift from ask- ing how workers reacted to inequitable payments to how they attempted to create equitable pay- ments. Research of this proactive content type continues, and is especially popular among Euro- pean social scientists. For example, recent repre- sentative efforts have focused on issues such as: (a) the distinctions allocators make between vari- ous types of contributions in making fair alloca- tions (Tornblom & Jonsson, 1985), (b) the commit- ment to justice principles among different classes of people (Montada, Schmitt, & Dalbert, 1986), Table 2 Representative Research Questions and Dependent Measures for Each Type of Organizational Justice Theory Type of Theory Representative Question Prototypical Dependent Measures Reactive Content How do workers react to inequitable Reactions to overpayment or underpayment payments? inequity (reviewed by Greenberg, 1982) Proactive Content How do workers attempt to create fair Adherence to justice norms in reward allocations payments? (reviewed by Freedman & Montanari, 1980) Reactive Process How do workers react to unfair policies Reactions to unfair payment methods or dispute- or legal procedures? resolution methods (reviewed by Folger & Greenberg, 1985) Proactive Process How do workers attempt to create fair Perceptions of procedural fairness (reviewed by policies or procedures? Lind & Tyler, in press) 16 and (c) the reliance upon considerations of need in the attainment of justice (Schwinger, 1986). With the continuation of such research there appears to be developing a better understand- ing of the ways workers behave in the interest of being fair. When Thibaut and Walker (1975) began their research on procedural justice in the early 1970s, it was not a reaction against the shortcomings of reactive process theories. Rather, it was inspired by an interest in the attributes of various dispute- resolution techniques. It was theorists such as Deutsch (1975) and Leventhal (1976b) who first pointed out that procedural justice research may be viewed as an extension of equity theory research into the domain of allocation processes. Folger (1977) was among the first researchers whose work reflected a shift from how workers react to inequitable outcomes to how they react to unfair procedures. His work showed that giv- ing workers the opportunity to have a voice in the decisions affecting them under some condi- tions enhanced their reactions to the outcome of those decisions (for a review, see Greenberg & Folger, 1983). The question of how workers react to various organizational procedures is not only the newest one to interest organizational justice researchers, but also one of the most actively researched areas today (for a statement on the state of the science, see Greenberg & Tyler, in press). Indeed, the attention procedural j ustice has received in recent professional symposia (e.g., Folger, 1986) and special publications devoted to the topic (Greenberg & Tyler, in press; Lind & Tyler, in press) attests to the current high level of interest in applying proactive process orientations to the study of organizational justice. As more organi- zational researchers continue to develop a rap- prochement between their interests and a pro- cess orientation to justice, there has been a shift away from legal-based questions regarding fair procedures to more organizationally based ques- tions. The growing body of research and theory considering these questions promises to extend our knowledge of organizational justice. For example, the present taxonomy proves to be useful in tracing the conceptual roots of two rapidly evolving and related lines of theory development in organizational justice. One of these, Folger's (1986, in press) referent cogni- tions theory, expands upon relative deprivation theory and equity theory when explaining rela- tive satisfaction with work outcomes. The theory extends the reactive content orientation of its pre- decessors by distinguishing between two types of reactions-those based on relative com- parisons, leading to feelings of dissatisfactiono, and those based on beliefs about what should have happened, leading to feelings of resent- ment and moral outrage. Resentment reactions are theorized to be based on the procedures used to bring about various outcomes, whereas satis- faction with those outcomes is based on beliefs about the relative outcome levels themselves. In terms of the present taxonomy, it can be said that referent cognitions theory expands the con- cept of relative deprivation to a process prospec- tive beyond its more traditional, content per- spective. Similarly, related research by Bies (1987; Bies & Moag, 1986) focuses on feelings of moral out- rage. Bies asserts that justice perceptions are better explained by the social accounts given for them than by the appearance of an inequity based on comparisons of relative outcomes and inputs. Social accounts of events-including those that claim mitigating circumstances, in- voke superordinate ideological goals, refer to likely future states, and offer apologies for cur- rent states-are offered as likely determinants of reactions to injustice. Bies also claims that social accounts can be used to explain reactions to out- come distribution procedures as well as the out- come distributions themselves. As such, Bies's conceptualization, like Folger's, provides a framework for integrating process-based and the content-based reactions to injustice. In addition, Bies's work sheds some light on an important deficiency of reactive theories of organizational justice-namely, the conditions under which dif- ferent reactions are likely to be exhibited. 17 The present taxonomy helps us recognize the conceptual traditions from which new theoreti- cal developments, such as those of Folger (1986) and Bies (1987) were derived, and as such facili- tates appreciation for their integrative nature. Thinking of these developments as markers of justice theories, the taxonomy may be viewed as a road map that helps chart the course of theoreti- cal progress. Identifying Needed Areas of Research and Theory By highlighting the relationships between the various types of organizational justice theories, the present taxonomy helps identify areas of the- oretical and empirical deficiency. In particular, it helps spot research areas across categories in which parallel types of investigations have not been undertaken. Most notable are questions stemming from the proactive process orientation. In the abstract, this should not be surprising given that the proactive process approach is the new- est theoretical approach to organizational justice. However, questions should be asked about the type of research that needs to be conducted in this area relative to that which already has been done. As described earlier, in studies inspired by the proactive process, subjects were asked either to generate and categorize lists of per- ceived fair/unfair job behaviors or to assess the importance of various theoretically derived pro- cedural determinants of fairness manipulated in written scenarios. Both types of research essen- tially serve as validation studies of the research from which they were derived. Although these investigations are useful, they are not parallel to those found in the proactive content category because how subjects make procedural decisions was not observed directly. Although in proactive content studies the resource allocation decisions made by subjects are observed under a variety of different con- ditions (see Freedman & Montanari, 1980), in- vestigators interested in procedural issues have as of yet conducted analogous studies. Indeed, a program of research designed to determine the conditions under which people make vari- ous procedural decisions would be useful to the- ory development in the proactive process area. Two types of investigations are warranted. First, laboratory studies could be conducted in which personal and situational factors are manipulated to see how they influence decisions about what procedures should be used. Second, a post hoc, policy-capturing investigation could be done in which investigators analyze the conditions under which various actual procedural decisions are made. One area in which a contribution of the pres- ent taxonomy may be realized is pay satisfaction. In particular, Heneman (1985) identified "pay poli- cies and administration" as a class of variables that need to be included in his model of pay satisfaction. Citing evidence (Dyer & Theriault, 1976; Weiner, 1980) showing that understanding how pay raises were determined added to the explained variance in pay satisfaction beyond pay level alone, Heneman (1985) concluded that "perceptions about how pay is administered do appear to have a bearing on people's pay satis- faction" (p. 132). In making this claim for a direc- tion in which to extend theories of pay satisfac- tion beyond equity theory, Heneman recognized the distinction between content and process the- ories of organizational justice articulated here. Heneman's insight may have been realized ear- lier given the present taxonomy. Still, seeing how well the taxonomy fits Heneman's conceptualiza- tion provides encouragement for using it to derive further insight about pay satisfaction. Indeed, process theories of organizational justice may be used to suggest factors likely to enhance satis- faction with pay and the consequences of per- ceived unfair pay-determination practices. Finally, it should be noted that the present tax- onomy provides a useful framework for appreci- ating the context within which several newly emerging lines of research are derived. For example, Greenberg's line of research on perfor- mance appraisal (Greenberg, 1986b, in press) was inspired by attempts to apply research and theory on procedural justice to employee eval- uation situations. Similarly, Sheppard's (1985) efforts at applying his model of organizational 18 dispute resolution (1984) were inspired by a tradi- tion of research applying procedural justice notions to legal disputes. Both these lines of research represent areas made salient by the present taxonomy. Conclusion In 1966, Weick referred to equity theory as "among the more useful middle-range theories of organizational behavior" (p. 439). In 1984, Miner classified equity theory among those in his list of "not so useful" theories of organiza- tional behavior. Equity theory has fallen into disfavor partially because of its limited applica- bility and partially because of its internal valid- ity as a theory (Furby, 1986). Also it may be because researchers have grown weary of the restricted range of questions about organizational justice it addresses. Yet, questions about justice still arise in many organizational milieus, among them contexts as diverse as pay plans (compar- able worth) (Mahoney, 1983), grievance proce- dures, selection and placement practices, and evaluation policies (Folger & Greenberg, 1985; Greenberg & Folger, 1983). The questions raised about justice in these contexts are not ones that equity theory, or any of the other reactive con- tent theories, are equipped to address. However, there are other theories of organizational justice presented in this article that may be particularly well-suited to such matters. To the extent that the taxonomy presented in this article has brought them to the attention of organizational resear- chers, then it has paved the way for increased understanding to emerge an understanding of various organizational phenomena, and of jus- tice itself. References Adams, J. S. (1965) Inequity in social exchange. In L. Berko- witz (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 2, pp. 267-299). New York: Academic Press. Adams, J. S., & Freedman, S. (1976) Equity theory revisited: Comments and annotated bibliography. In L. Berkowitz & E. Walster (Eds.), Advances in experimental social psy- chology (Vol. 9, pp. 43-90). New York: Academic Press. Adams, J. S., & Rosenbaum, W. B. (1962) The relationship of worker productivity to cognitive dissonance about wage inequities. Journal of Applied Psychology, 46, 161-164. Anderson, B., Berger, J., Zelditch, M., & Cohen, B. P. (1969) Reactions to inequity. Acta Sociologica, 12, 1-12. Aram, J. D., & Salipante, P. F., Jr. (1981) An evaluation of organizational due process in the resolution of employee/ employer conflict. Academy of Management Review, 6, 197-204. Arvey, R. D. (1979) Fairness in selecting employees. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley. Barrett-Howard, E., & Tyler, T. R. (1986) Procedural justice as a criterion in allocation decisions. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 50, 296-304. Berger, J., Zelditch, M., Anderson, B., & Cohen, B. P. (1972) Structural aspects of distributive justice: A status-value formulation. In J. Berger, M. Zelditch, & B. Anderson (Eds.), Sociological theories in progress (Vol. 2, pp. 21-45). Boston: Houghton Mifflin. Bies, R. J. (1987) The predicament of injustice. The manage- ment of moral outrage. In L. L. Cummings & B. M. Staw (Eds.), Research in organizational behavior (Vol. 9, pp. 289-319). Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. Bies, R. J., & Moag, J. S. (1986) Interactional justice: Commu- nication criteria of fairness. In R. J. Lewicki, B. H. Sheppard, & M. H. Bazerman (Eds.), Research on negotiation in organizations (Vol. 1, pp. 43-55). Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. Campbell, J. P., & Pritchard, R. A. (1976) Motivation theory in industrial and organizational psychology. In M. D. Dunnette (Ed.), Handbook of industrial and organizational psychology (pp. 63-130). Chicago: Rand McNally. Carles, E. M., & Carver, C. S. (1979) Effects of person salience versus role salience on reward allocation in the dyad. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 37, 2071-2080. Cohen, R. L., & Greenberg, J. (1982) The justice concept in social psychology. In J. Greenberg & R. L. Cohen (Eds.), Equity and justice in social behavior (pp. 1-41). New York: Academic Press. Cosier, R. A., & Dalton, D. R. (1983) Equity theory and time: A reformulation. Academy of Management Review, 8, 311-319. Crosby, F. (1976) A model of egoistical relative deprivation. Psychological Review, 83, 85-113. Crosby, F. (1982) Relative deprivation and working women. New York: Oxford University Press. 19 Crosby, F. (1984) Relative deprivation in organizational settings. In B. M. Staw & L. L. Cummings (Eds.), Research in organizational behavior (Vol. 6, pp. 51-93). Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. Dalton, D. R., & Todor, W. D. (1985a) Gender and workplace justice: A field assessment. Personnel Psychology, 38, 133-151. Dalton, D. R., & Todor, W. D. (1985b) Composition of dyads as a factor in the outcomes of workplace justice: Two field assessments. Academy of Management Journal, 28, 704- 712. Deutsch, M. (1975) Equity, equality and need: What deter- mines which value will be used as the basis for distribu- tive justice? Journal of Social Issues, 31(3), 137-149. Deutsch, M. (1985) Distributive justice. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Dyer, L., & Theriault, R. (1976) The determinants of pay satisfaction. Journal of Applied Psychology, 61, 596-604. Festinger, L. (1957) A theory of cognitive dissonance. Evans- ton, IL: Row, Peterson. Folger, R. (1977) Distributive and procedural justice: Com- bined impact of "voice" and improvement on experienced inequity. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 35, 108-119. Folger, R. (Chair) (1986, April) Fairness is more than equity: New approaches to studying organizational injustice. Sym- posium presented at the first annual conference of the Society for Industrial and Organizational Psychology, Chicago. Folger, R. (1986) Rethinking equity theory: A referent cogni- tions model. In H. W. Bierhoff, R. L. Cohen, & J. Greenberg (Eds.), Justice in social relations (pp. 145-162). New York: Plenum. Folger, R. (in press) Reformulating the preconditions of resentment: A referent cognitions model. In J. C. Masters & W. P. Smith (Eds.), Social comparison, social justice, and relative deprivation: Theoretical, empirical, and pol- icy perspectives. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Folger, R., & Greenberg, J. (1985) Procedural justice: An inter- pretive analysis of personnel systems. In K. Rowland & G. Ferris (Eds.), Research in personnel and human resources management (Vol. 3, pp. 141-183). Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. Freedman, S. M., & Montanari, J. R. (1980) An integrative model of managerial reward allocation. Academy of Man- agement Review, 5, 381-390. Fry, W. R., & Cheney, G. (1981, May) Perceptions of proce- dural fairness as a function of distributive preference. Paper presented at the meeting of the Midwestern Psycho- logical Association, Detroit. Fry, W. R., & Leventhal, G. S. (1979, March) Cross-situational procedural preferences: A comparison of allocation prefer- ences and equity across different social settings. In A. Lind (Chair), The psychology of procedural justice. Sympo- sium conducted at the meeting of the Southwestern Psy- chological Association, Washington, DC. Fuller, L. (1961) The adversary system. In H. Berman (Ed.), Talks on American law (pp. 10-22). New York: Vintage Books. Furby, L. (1986) Psychology and justice. In R. L. Cohen (Ed.), Justice: Views from the social sciences (pp. 153-203). New York: Plenum. Garland, H. (1973) The effects of piece-rate underpayment and overpayment on job performance: A test of equity theory with a new induction procedure. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 3, 325-334. Goodman, P. S., & Friedman, A. (1971) An examination of Adams' theory of inequity. Administrative Science Quar- terly, 16, 271-288. Greenberg, J. (1982) Approaching equity and avoiding ineq- uity in groups and organizations. In J. Greenberg & R. L. Cohen (Eds.), Equity and justice in social behavior (pp. 389-435). New York: Academic Press. Greenberg, J. (1984) On the apocryphal nature of inequity distress. In R. Folger (Ed.), The sense of injustice (pp. 167-188). New York: Plenum. Greenberg, J. (1986a) Determinants of perceived fairness of performance evaluations. Journal of Applied Psychology, 71, 340-342. Greenberg, J. (1986b) Organizational performance appraisal procedures: What makes them fair? In R. J. Lewicki, B. H. Sheppard, & M. Bazerman (Eds.), Research on negotia- tion in organizations (Vol. 1, pp. 25-41). Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. Greenberg, J. (in press) Using diaries to promote procedural justice in performance appraisals. Social Justice Review. Greenberg, J., & Cohen, R. L. (1982) Why justice? Normative and instrumental interpretations. In J. Greenberg & R. L. Cohen (Eds.), Equity and justice in social behavior (pp. 437-469). New York: Academic Press. Greenberg, J., & Folger, R. (1983) Procedural justice, partici- pation, and the fair process effect in groups and organiza- tions. In P. B. Paulus (Ed.), Basic group processes (pp. 235-256). New York: Springer-Verlag. Greenberg, J., & Leventhal, G. S. (1976) Equity and the use of overreward to motivate performance. Journal of Per- sonality and Social Psychology, 34, 179-190. Greenberg, J., & Ornstein, S. (1983) High status job title as compensation for underpayment: A test of equity theory. Journal of Applied Psychology, 68, 285-297. 20 Greenberg, J., & Tyler, T. (in press) Why procedural justice in organizations? Social Justice Review. Homans, G. C. (1961) Social behavior: Its elementary forms. New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World. Heider, F. (1958) The psychology of interpersonal relations. New York: Wiley. Heneman, H. G., 11 (1985) Pay satisfaction. In K. Rowland & G. Ferris (Eds.), Research in personnel and human re- sources management (Vol. 3, pp. 115-139). Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. lasso, G. (1980) A new theory of distributive justice. American Sociological Review, 45, 3-32. LaTour, S. (1978) Determinants of participant and observer satisfaction with adversary and inquisitorial modes of adjudication. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 36, 1531-1545. Lawler, E. E., III, & O'Gara, P.W. (1967) Effects of inequity produced by underpayment on work output, work quality, and attitudes toward the work. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 51, 403-410. Lerner, M. J. (1977) The justice motive: Some hypotheses as to its origins and forms. Journal of Personality, 45, 1-52. Lerner, M. J. (1982) The justice motive in human relations and the economic model of man: A radical analysis of facts and fictions. In V. Derlega & J. Greziak (Eds.), Cooperation and helping behavior: Theories and research (pp. 121-145). New York: Academic Press. Lerner, M. J., & Whitehead, L. A. (1980) Procedural justice viewed in the context of justice motive theory. In G. Mikula (Ed.), Justice and social interaction (pp. 219-256). New York: Springer-Verlag. Leventhal, G. S. (1976a) Fairness in social relationships. In J. W. Thibaut, J. T. Spence, & R. C. Carson (Eds.), Contem- porary topics in social psychology (pp. 211-239). Morris- town, NJ: General Learning Press. Leventhal, G. S. (1976b) The distribution of rewards and resources in groups and organizations. In L. Berkowitz & E. Walster (Eds.), Advances in experimental social psy- chology (Vol. 9, pp. 91-131). New York: Academic Press. Leventhal, G. S. (1980) What should be done with equity theory? In K. J. Gergen, M. S. Greenberg, & R. H. Willis (Eds.), Social exchange: Advances in theory and research (pp. 27-55). New York: Plenum. Leventhal, G. S., Karuza, J., & Fry, W. R. (1980) Beyond fairness: A theory of allocation preferences. In G. Mikula (Ed.), Justice and social interaction (pp. 167-218). New York: Springer-Verlag. Leventhal, G. S., & Michaels, J. W. (1969) Extending the equity model: Perceptions of inputs and allocation of reward as a function of duration and quantity of performance. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 12, 303-309. Lind, E. A., Kurtz, S., Musante, L., Walker, L., & Thibaut, J. W. (1980) Procedure and outcome effects on reactions to adjudicated resolution of conflicts of interest. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 39, 643-653. Lind, E.A., & Tyler, T.R. (in press) The social psychology of procedural justice. New York: Plenum. Mahoney, T. A. (1975) Justice and equity: A recurring theme in compensation. Personnel, 52(5), 60-66. Mahoney, T. A. (1983) Approaches to the definition of compa- rable worth. Academy of Management Review, 8, 14-22. Martin, J. (1981) Relative deprivation: A theory of distributive injustice for an era of shrinking resources. In L. L. Cum- mings & B. M. Staw (Eds.), Research in organizational behavior (Vol. 3, pp. 53-107). Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. Mess6, L. A. (1971) Equity in bilateral bargaining. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 17, 287-291. Mikula, G. (1980) On the role of justice in allocation decisions. In G. Mikula (Ed.), Justice and social interaction (pp. 127-165). New York: Springer-Verlag. Miner, J. B. (1984) The unpaved road over the mountains: From theory to applications. Industrial-Organizational Psy- chologist, 21(2), 9-20. Montada, L., Schmitt, M., & Dalbert, C. (1986) Thinking about justice and dealing with one's own privileges: A study of existential guilt. In H. W. Bierhoff, R. L. Cohen, & J. Greenberg (Eds.), Justice in social relations (pp. 125-143). New York: Plenum. Pritchard, R. A. (1969) Equity theory: A review and critique. Organizational Behavior and Human Performance, 4, 75-94. Pritchard, R. D., Dunnette, M. D., & Jorgenson, D. 0. (1972) Effects of perceptions of equity and inequity on worker performance and satisfaction. Journal of Applied Psychol- ogy, 56, 75-94. Reis, H. T. (1986) Levels of interest in the study of interper- sonal justice. In H. W. Bierhoff, R. L. Cohen, & J. Greenberg (Eds.), Justice in social relations (pp. 187-209). New York: Plenum. Schwinger, T. (1980) Just allocations of goods: Decisions among three principles. In G. Mikula (Ed.), Justice and social interaction (pp. 95-125). New York: Springer-Verlag. Schwinger, T. (1986) The need principle of distributive justice. In H. W. Bierhoff, R. L. Cohen, & J. Greenberg (Eds.), Justice in social relations (pp. 211-225). New York: Plenum. Sheppard, B. H. (1984) Third party conflict intervention: A procedural framework. In B. M. Staw & L. L. Cummings (Eds.), Research in organizational behavior (Vol. 6, pp. 141-190). Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. 21 Sheppard, B. H. (1985) Justice is no simple matter: Case for elaborating our model of procedural fairness. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 49, 953-962. Sheppard, B. H., & Lewicki, R. J. (in press) Toward general principles of managerial fairness. Social Justice Review. Stouffer, S. A., Suchman, E. A., DeVinney, L. C., Star, S. A., & Williams, R. M., Jr. (1949) The American soldier: Adjust- ment during Army life (Vol. 1). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Thibaut, J., & Walker, L. (1975) Procedural justice: A psycho- logical analysis. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Thibaut, J., & Walker, L. (1978) A theory of procedure. California Law Review, 66, 541-566. Tornblom, K.Y., & Jonsson, D.R. (1985) Subrules of the equal- ity and contribution principles: Their perceived fairness in distribution and retribution. Social Psychology Quarterly, 48, 249-261. Tyler, T. R., & Caine, A. (1981) The role of distributional and procedural fairness in the endorsement of formal leaders. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 41, 642-655. Tyler, T. R., & Folger, R. (1980) Distributional and procedural aspects of satisfaction with citizen-police encounters. Basic and Applied Social Psychology, 1, 281-292. Van Avermaet, E., McClintock, C., & Moskowitz, J. (1978) Alternative approaches to equity: Dissonance reduction, pro-social motivation and strategies accommodation. European Journal of Social Psychology, 8, 419-437. Walker, L., Lind, E. A., & Thibaut, J. (1979) The relation between procedural justice and distributive justice. Virginia Law Review, 65, 1401-1420. Walster, E., Berscheid, E., & Walster, G. W. (1 973) New direc- tions in equity research. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 25, 151-176. Walster, E., Walster, G. W., & Berscheid, E. (1978) Equity: Theory and research. Boston: Allyn & Bacon. Walton, R. W., & McKersie, R. B. (1965) A behavioral theory of labor negotiations. New York: McGraw-Hill. Weick, K. E. (1966) The concept of equity in the perception of pay. Administrative Science Quarterly, I1, 414-439. Weiner, N. (1980) Determinants and behavioral consequences of pay satisfaction: A comparison of two models. Personnel Psychology, 33, 741-757. Jerald Greenberg (Ph.D., Wayne State University) is Associate Professor of Management and Human Re- sources at Ohio State University. Correspondence regarding this article may be addressed to him at: Faculty of Management and Human Resources, Ohio State University, 1775 College Road, Columbus, OH 43210-1399. 22 Article Contents p. 9 p. 10 p. 11 p. 12 p. 13 p. 14 p. 15 p. 16 p. 17 p. 18 p. 19 p. 20 p. 21 p. 22 Issue Table of Contents The Academy of Management Review, Vol. 12, No. 1 (Jan., 1987), pp. 1-216 Front Matter [pp. 1 - 8] A Taxonomy of Organizational Justice Theories [pp. 9 - 22] Expression of Emotion as Part of the Work Role [pp. 23 - 37] Are the Classical Management Functions Useful in Describing Managerial Work? [pp. 38 - 51] The Escalation Phenomenon Reconsidered: Decision Dilemmas or Decision Errors? [pp. 52 - 66] Corporate Strategy: Useful Perspective for the Study of Capital Structure? [pp. 67 - 75] Categorizing Strategic Issues: Links to Organizational Action [pp. 76 - 90] Strategic Control: A New Perspective [pp. 91 - 103] The Concept of Ideology in Organizational Analysis: The Sociology of Knowledge or the Social Psychology of Beliefs? [pp. 104 - 116] Congruence, Contingency, and Theory Building [pp. 117 - 132] Three Types of Perceived Uncertainty about the Environment: State, Effect, and Response Uncertainty [pp. 133 - 143] Political-Cultural Analysis of Organizations [pp. 144 - 156] The College Sophomore as Guinea Pig: Setting the Record Straight [pp. 157 - 159] Student Guinea Pigs: Porcine Predictors and Particularistic Phenomena [pp. 160 - 163] Book Reviews The "All Things in Moderation" Leader [pp. 164 - 169] untitled [pp. 169 - 171] untitled [pp. 171 - 172] untitled [pp. 172 - 175] untitled [pp. 175 - 177] Publications Received [pp. 178 - 180] Textbook Review Three Down-Loaded Mainframe Business Games: A Review [pp. 181 - 192] Back Matter [pp. 193 - 216] work_2gbv3mdbjvfczovo5kok6x7zvq ---- UAR301790.qxd Minority Empowerment and Environmental Justice Stefanie Chambers Trinity College, Hartford, Connecticut In Hartford, Connecticut, environmental health problems disproportionately affect poor and minority residents of the city. Minority group activists in Hartford have created a multiracial organization composed of urban and sub- urban residents to fight for environmental justice. The organization has achieved a measure of success in terms of governmental responsiveness to their concerns. This article highlights the strategies used by the organization to advance its interests. These strategies are framed within the minority empowerment and environmental justice literature to develop a theoretical explanation for the organization’s success. Additionally, this article provides a model for other communities fighting for environmental justice. Keywords: environmental justice; minority empowerment; public health The Hartford Environmental Justice Network (HEJN) is an organizationcomprised largely of minorities from impoverished neighborhoods in Hartford, Connecticut. The initial formation of HEJN stemmed from com- munity concerns about the negative effects of industrial facilities sited near residential areas. An additional catalyst and a continuing focus for the orga- nization is the perception that racial minorities and low-income residents of Hartford are disproportionately burdened by the negative environmental and health consequences of industrial facilities. Today, the organization includes approximately 1,800 individual grassroots members as well as approximately 30 member organizations. HEJN is now a powerful and active organization that has attracted the attention and respect of other stakeholders including local, state, and federal government officials. Through an examination of HEJN’s organizational structure and strate- gies, this article presents a case study of a successful minority-led, yet mul- tiracial environmental organization. Success is operationalized in this study as the organization’s ability to achieve a response by public officials to the issues on HEJN’s agenda. A key determinant of success is the ability of the Urban Affairs Review Volume 43 Number 1 September 2007 28-54 © 2007 Sage Publications 10.1177/1078087407301790 http://uar.sagepub.com hosted at http://online.sagepub.com 28 Author’s Note: I would like to thank Diana Evans, Jerry Watts, the UAR editors, and several anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments. distribution. © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized at SUNY AT BUFFALO on August 27, 2007 http://uar.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://uar.sagepub.com group to maintain an ongoing organizational structure that continuously pushes for environmental policies that benefit the community. To accom- plish this, the group utilizes a combination of strategies including main- taining a racially and ethnically diverse membership, providing members with technical training, building coalitions with existing community orga- nizations in the Greater Hartford area, fostering leadership skills among members, and moving toward institutionalized forms of political participa- tion now that they are viewed as legitimate actors in the policy arena. These tactics have not only made HEJN effective, but have also mobilized members in unique ways and led to considerable minority empowerment. By examining the organizational structure and strategies of a multiracial environmental justice group, this case study builds upon the minority empowerment and environmental justice literature by providing a model of a stable multiracial coalition that achieves policy responsiveness. In the sections that follow, I first present an overview of the relevant environmental justice and minority empowerment literature. The next sec- tion provides an overview of Hartford demographics and the environmen- tal challenges faced by the greater Hartford region. I then discuss the creation of HEJN and their policy focus, followed by a section on the pol- icy responsiveness achieved by the organization. Next, I outline the organi- zational strategy used by the organization to maintain sustained mobilization. The final section reconnects the environmental justice and minority empow- erment literature to the HEJN model: a sustained multiracial coalition in the environmental justice policy arena. Literature Review: Environmental Justice and Minority Empowerment Scholars of minority empowerment examine the ways in which minor- ity political participation can become more effective and institutionalized (Bobo and Gilliam 1990; Browning, Marshall, and Tabb 1984, 2003; Eisinger 1982; Fung 2004). However, most of the minority empowerment literature focuses on protest and electoral strategies that contribute to the political incorporation of minorities into the political structures of their communities. Environmental justice groups, by contrast, are concerned with electoral outcomes as a strategy for affecting environmental policy. Although they frequently participate in protest activities to advance their short-term agenda, their larger goals are more comprehensive: They seek to influence the policy process long-term and overcome their own marginaliza- tion in the political system. This study explores the nonelectoral strategies Chambers / Minority Empowerment and Environmental Justice 29 distribution. © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized at SUNY AT BUFFALO on August 27, 2007 http://uar.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://uar.sagepub.com and organizational structure of a multiracial environmental justice organi- zation to gain insight into how such organizations can maintain coalitional stability and achieve long-term policy goals. Neither the minority empow- erment nor the environmental justice literature indicates how these things could occur. Examining HEJN in this light provides instructive findings for similar organizations and makes an important contribution to these two bodies of scholarship. The environmental justice literature offers many examples of successful struggles for environmental justice by poor people and minorities (Bullard 1993, 1994, 2000; Bullard and Johnson 2000; Capek 1993; Checker 2001; Mohai and Bryant 1992; Taylor 1995). Survey research documents the fact that Blacks (and other minority groups) share with Whites a deep concern about the environment (Bullard, Warren, and Johnson 2001; Jones 1998; Taylor 1989; Mohai 2003). The only difference is that Blacks express greater concern with pollution in neighborhoods and other aspects of local environmental quality. It is this difference that makes Blacks more likely to engage in the environmental justice movement. Although the environmental justice scholarship is best known for provid- ing case studies of specific mobilization by coalitions that rise and fall with a given issue, there are also theoretical models for ongoing environmental jus- tice activism within this research. One case study, by anthropologist Melissa Checker (2001), examines how a multiethnic group in Brooklyn, New York, mobilized around environmental justice in their city by creating a shared identity focused primarily on discrimination while retaining rich ethnic diver- sity among group members. In another theoretical model, Dorchetta Taylor (1989, 199) argues that to increase Black environmental activism, several pre- requisites must be met including group solidarity, resources (money, knowl- edge, morale), and psychological factors (ideology and discontent). Even with these important studies, it is unclear whether long-term environmental activism will occur or whether responsive governmental policies will result from this activism. Nevertheless, in commenting on the environmental justice literature, Robert Bullard (2000, 89) points out, “very little is known about . . . the factors that propel or impede Black mobilization against environmental threats.11 This article builds upon the existing literature by demonstrating how a multiracial environmental justice organization can maintain institutional stability, particularly by uniting city and suburban residents, to achieve policy objectives. Within the minority empowerment literature, Rufus P. Browning, Dale Rogers Marshall, and David H. Tabb (BMT) (1984) create a theoretical framework that is useful for examining how multiracial coalitions can 30 Urban Affairs Review distribution. © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized at SUNY AT BUFFALO on August 27, 2007 http://uar.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://uar.sagepub.com Chambers / Minority Empowerment and Environmental Justice 31 advance minority interests. In fact, their findings with regard to multiracial coalitions are relevant to the experiences of HEJN. The authors identify ways that minorities can become a significant political force and achieve substantive gains from local government. By examining the struggles for political access and responsive policies of minority groups in 10 California cities, they find that mobilization (protest, electoral participation, or a combination of the two) can lead to minority political incorporation in city government (elective or appointed positions), and ultimately policies that are responsive to minority concerns. However, policy responsiveness to the interests of the minority community is the ultimate measure of suc- cess because the minority community is affected by policy decisions. The authors also argue that biracial or multiracial coalitions are a way for Blacks and Latinos to gain political power provided that group resources and other conditions are favorable. These group resources and conditions include factors such as group size, concentration, cohesion, and organizational strength. BMT also argue that mobilization of resources alone is not usually enough to propel minority groups into political power, but that to achieve success, minorities need to acquire the support of other minorities and/or liberal Whites. In other words, biracial or multiracial coalitions are a way for Blacks and Latinos to gain political power and policy responsiveness. At the same time that BMT place emphasis on multiracial coalitions, other scholars argue that these coalitions frequently encounter problems in terms of coalitional stability (DeLeon 2003; Hero and Clarke 2003; Mollenkopf 2003; Orr 2003; Owens and Rich 2003; Perry 2003; Pinderhughes 2003). These coalitions are often short-lived; even in situations where minorities are able to elect minority mayors, the mayors often face fiscal situations that force them to turn their back on minority interests in favor of business interests. Furthermore, even in nonelectoral situations, multiracial coalitions are often limited because racial groups have different overall interests that frequently interfere with overarching and stable coalitions. Another relevant finding from the BMT framework is the idea that action by the federal government has the potential to enhance the impact of minority political empowerment (1984, 213). Specifically, BMT examined federal social programs from the 1960s aimed at eradicating poverty in urban areas. Minority respondents in their study indicated that these federal programs provided more opportunities for minority mobilization, minority incorporation in the policy process, and policies that reflected the interests of the minority populations. distribution. © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized at SUNY AT BUFFALO on August 27, 2007 http://uar.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://uar.sagepub.com The notion that federal intervention helps to advance the interests of minority groups is apparent if we look at both federal antipoverty programs and civil rights legislation, as do BMT. Action by the federal government is typically the result of intense pressure by the oppressed group. One need only to think of the civil rights movement and the enforcement of voting rights for an example. This is not to say that the federal government is always sympathetic to the situation of racial and ethnic minorities, but that social movements in the United States have frequently established the objective of changing federal policy to reach the ideals of democratic inclu- sion. At times, this has meant pushing for the fulfillment of constitutional rights such as the right to vote. At other times, it has meant convincing pol- icy makers to enact laws to guarantee equal treatment of an oppressed group. Executive orders and laws dealing with affirmative action or envi- ronmental equality fall under this category. Archon Fung (2004), another contributor to the minority empowerment literature, argues that democratic participation not only empowers minori- ties, but also makes public institutions more effective and capable of pro- ducing social change. More important, he believes that democracy requires individuals to “have substantial and equal opportunities to participate directly in decisions that affect them” (2004, 4). By examining the ways in which community members in several Chicago neighborhoods united to create more effective schools and to reduce crime, he demonstrates that when previously disempowered groups organize they can become players in the policy process and make municipal agencies more effective. His research also suggests that without the democratic empowerment of under- represented groups, municipal governments are less effective and useful for minorities. The common themes present in both the environmental justice and minority empowerment literature provide an ideal theoretical backdrop to an analysis of HEJN and the organization’s ability to create a sustainable and multiracial organization. Both bodies of scholarship discuss the impor- tance of group resources (such as size, cohesion, solidarity, organizational strength) and racial/ethnic diversity as factors for success. It is also clear that shared experiences, particularly as they relate to group marginalization, help mobilize groups to take action. At the same time that the literature in these fields provides some direction for organizational success, we are left with a dilemma: How can effective minority coalitions be sustained over time? This study presents the organizational strategies used by an environ- mental justice organization to create a sustained organization that achieves policy responsiveness.1 32 Urban Affairs Review distribution. © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized at SUNY AT BUFFALO on August 27, 2007 http://uar.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://uar.sagepub.com Hartford: Diversity and Environmental Challenges Formerly known as the insurance capitol of the world, Hartford is attempt- ing to recast its image as “New England’s Rising Star.” Despite this slogan and some recent high-profile development projects in the core downtown area, the city continues to struggle. In 2002, the New York Times character- ized Hartford as “the most destitute 17 square miles in the nation’s wealthi- est state” because of racial isolation and poverty within Hartford as compared to the city’s suburbs (Zielbauer, 2002, A1). Since the late 1980s, this capitol city has struggled as insurance companies moved to suburbs or outside the state and as the region experienced a decline in defense industry production. Within the city’s 17.4 square miles there are approximately 121,000 resi- dents. For the past 40 years, the non-Hispanic White population in the city has been steadily decreasing. In the past decade, there has been a 50% decline among these residents. According to the 2000 U.S. Census, the largest racial/ethnic groups in the city are Hispanics (40%), followed by Blacks (38%). Interestingly, Hartford’s Hispanics are overwhelmingly Puerto Rican (80%), and among Blacks, one in four is of West Indian descent. Poverty has been a persistent problem in Hartford. In 1999, a staggering 31% of city residents lived in poverty for part of the year (Kuzyk 2003, 69). This figure makes Hartford the poorest city in the state. Another indicator of poverty is the percentage of students eligible for free school lunches. In 2002, 60.4% of Hartford’s public school students were eligible for this program, in comparison to 22% of students statewide.2 The 2000 U.S. Census reported the median household income in Hartford in 1999 at $24,829, which was approximately half of the median household income among the city’s inner ring suburbs. Hartford also has the lowest home ownership rate in the nation at 24.6%, compared to the statewide average of 67% (2000 U.S. Census). Hartford is not the only city in Connecticut facing challenges. The 2000 U.S. Census revealed that although the state is one of the wealthiest in the nation, it also includes some of the nation’s poorest cities such as Hartford, Bridgeport, New Haven, and Waterbury. At the same time, these impoverished cities are also home to the state’s most polluted sites. The toxics map in Figure 1 illustrates the strong relationship between minority communities and the location of toxic pollutants and waste in the state. Areas with the highest concentration of toxins happen to be located in Connecticut’s poorest cities where large numbers of minority residents live. These findings are not unusual. Many scholars have identi- fied a correlation between communities of color and the location of haz- ardous waste facilities (Bullard and Wright 1987; Myers 2004; Walker, Chambers / Minority Empowerment and Environmental Justice 33 distribution. © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized at SUNY AT BUFFALO on August 27, 2007 http://uar.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://uar.sagepub.com 34 Urban Affairs Review Mays, and Warren 2004; Wright 1998).3 Figure 1 also reflects the research by Timothy Black and John A. Stewart (2001) on the concentration of regional waste disposal incinerators and landfills in the state of Connecticut. Black and Stewart found that these facilities tend to be near neighborhoods with higher concentrations of poor and minority residents. In fact, when they controlled for other factors, race and ethnicity remained the single best predictor of siting decisions in the state. Although there has not been a comprehensive study of Hartford regard- ing whether minorities bear a disproportionate burden of environmental haz- ards, given the large number of minorities in the city and the numerous toxic industrial facilities located near predominately minority neighborhoods, it is quite likely that Hartford mirrors the findings of Black and Stewart. Indeed, the areas of Hartford with the greatest concentration of environmentally haz- ardous facilities are located within minority neighborhoods. These facilities Figure 1 Toxics Map Source: Department of Environmental Protection and 2000 U.S. Census distribution. © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized at SUNY AT BUFFALO on August 27, 2007 http://uar.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://uar.sagepub.com Chambers / Minority Empowerment and Environmental Justice 35 include a trash to energy plant and a regional landfill that serve the trash disposal needs of approximately 70 neighboring towns—most of which have far lower percentages of minority residents than does Hartford. HEJN: Origins and Policy Focus Mobilization of Hartford’s minority community around environmental justice began in the early 1990s when ONE CHANE, one of Hartford’s north end neighborhood organizations, initiated protests against a local landfill.4 This landfill is located in the north end of Hartford in a predomi- nately Black and impoverished neighborhood. It was not the fact that it was located in this community per se that convinced people to fight the landfill. Rather, it was the rising rate of health problems of local residents, who became convinced that there was a relationship between their declining health and the odors from the landfill. As one resident commented, The smell was awful. Birds were dropping from the sky and dogs were dying. People were getting sick. We knew it was from the landfill (activist interview, February 18, 2002). Concerned community members reported the situation to the city health department. The health commissioner at the time, an African-American public health physician named Mark Mitchell, became convinced that the gasses emitted from the landfill were related to the complaints of local res- idents. Dr. Mitchell explained: I started getting involved due to the complaints about the odors at the land- fill. The landfill operator, Connecticut Resources Recovery Authority (CRRA), and the DEP (Connecticut Department of Environmental Protection) were unresponsive. I knew that a well run landfill should not have odors and I knew that DEP and the city had enforcement power over the landfill (presi- dent of HEJN, interview, March 14, 2002). Dr. Mitchell merged his scientific training and his concern for the health of north Hartford residents with his understanding of the legal oversight of the landfill. Since 1987, the landfill has been operated by the CRRA, a quasi-governmental organization. The city’s contract with CRRA for trash disposal includes no date for the closure of the landfill, no requirements for negotiating trash disposal agreements with other cities and states, and vague language on the health and safety regulations for the landfill. As one distribution. © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized at SUNY AT BUFFALO on August 27, 2007 http://uar.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://uar.sagepub.com community activist explained, these made it impossible for local residents to influence a policy with enormous health ramifications, and prompted Dr. Mitchell to begin to address the problem (activist interview, March 14, 2002). Dr. Mitchell began to work closely with the minority community to pressure CRRA and the city of Hartford to hold CRRA more accountable for their practices; as a result, he was forced to resign in 1995 as the city’s health commissioner (activist interview, March 14, 2002; Hartford’s Environmental Public Health Educator, interview, April 22, 2002). Dr. Mitchell subsequently established Mitchell Health Consultants, an organization that wrote grants to fund local environmental justice efforts. ONE CHANE began working with Mitchell Health Consultants in 1995 to close the landfill. In 1995, ONE CHANE filed a federal lawsuit, claiming that the current landfill arrangements violated Title VI of the Civil Rights Act by virtue of the burden it placed on the minority community. That same year, ONE CHANE formed a coalition with the National Association for the Advancement of Colored People (NAACP) Legal Defense Fund, the NRDC (Natural Resource Defense Council), and the Connecticut Fund for the Environment; the coalition accused CRRA of environmental racism as evidenced by the siting of environmentally risky facilities in predominately African-American communities (activist interview, February 22, 2002). As a result of mounting pressure, CRRA initiated a major cleanup effort of the landfill to eliminate odors and resolve the disputes that were beginning to tarnish its reputation. By the end of 1995 the organization had spent roughly $13 million to clean up the landfill (activist interview, February 20, 2002, b). In 1996, ONE CHANE and CRRA negotiated an agreement whereby ONE CHANE would stop protesting the landfill in exchange for the cleanup of the landfill.5 Members of ONE CHANE used traditional strategies and practices to protest the landfill. During 1995, members staged protests outside of CRRA’s headquarters, held marches that attracted media attention, and conducted door-to-door recruitment of neighborhood residents. Interestingly, the strategy adopted by ONE CHANE, with the help of Dr. Mitchell, was to emphasize the odors of the landfill as the primary focus of their protests. Many residents were concerned with increases in cancer and other health ailments. Because these health problems would have been difficult to link directly to the landfill, the odor issue was emphasized. This was a wise choice given that the odor issue was ultimately resolved.6 This choice also reflects the “symbolic framing” that Stella Capek (1993) identifies in her work as a key to environmental justice organizing among people who do not possess scientific knowledge. 36 Urban Affairs Review distribution. © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized at SUNY AT BUFFALO on August 27, 2007 http://uar.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://uar.sagepub.com In 1997, Dr. Mitchell founded the HEJN which adopted a broader agenda than that originally pursued by ONE CHANE.7 From its inception, this organization has been devoted to protecting urban environments in Connecticut through educating our community, through promoting changes in state policy, and through promoting individual, corporate, and governmental responsibility towards our environment (HEJN mission statement). Although one of the organization’s primary goals is improving air qual- ity in the city, it is also concerned with all siting decisions that place an undue burden on communities of color. The organization is composed of about 30 member organizations, has approximately 1,800 individual members, and is roughly 80% minority (president of HEJN, interview, March 14, 2002).8 Building coalitions between groups is common among environ- mental justice groups. HEJN followed this strategy by creating an initial organization and then tapping into existing organizations to recruit repre- sentatives from other groups. This method was used so that the original organization would possess the capacity to exist independently as it brought in new groups with a similar interest in environmental justice. HEJN relies on financial support from local and national foundations and small contri- butions from members. One noteworthy difference between HEJN and other multiracial environ- mental justice organizations is that the organization is not ad hoc. HEJN has been a sustained force in Hartford’s environmental justice activism since 1997. Other studies of multiracial environmental justice coalitions show that these organizations typically rise and fall around a particular issue (Capek 1993). Environmental justice scholars have documented the success of a multiracial environmental justice group in Alabama, which succeeded in closing down a hazardous waste landfill (Bailey and Faupel 1992). Mark Moberg (2001) also found that a different multiracial environmental justice organization in Mobile, Alabama, was able to prevent the construction of a hazardous phenol plant in the area. In that case, upper class Whites began working with African-Americans when their attempts to prevent the build- ing of the plant failed. As a secondary strategy, they decided to reach out to African-Americans so they could file an environmental racism claim. Again, the key to these and other studies of multiracial environmental justice orga- nizations is that they are frequently ad hoc groups in the sense that once the issue at hand is resolved, they dissolve. This is especially the case when the organization begins as a White-dominated organization, as seen Chambers / Minority Empowerment and Environmental Justice 37 distribution. © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized at SUNY AT BUFFALO on August 27, 2007 http://uar.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://uar.sagepub.com in the Mobile case. HEJN does not suffer from this weakness. On the con- trary, it has been able to maintain a solid minority base. Achieving Policy Responsiveness Like ONE CHANE, HEJN initially engaged in protest tactics to advance its interests. The use of slogans such as “Hartford is the region’s dumping ground” and “We have the highest rates of asthma” were utilized to raise awareness and interest in HEJN’s mission (activist interview, February 15, 2002). Protests have been staged outside of city council meetings to push for recognition of issues such as what has been called the “asthma emergency.” HEJN has also protested at landfills and at the headquarters of companies that are engaged in environmentally haz- ardous activities. Their use of semantics is similar to the original use of the term environmental racism by Dr. Ben Chavis of the United Church of Christ in 1987 (CRJ 1987). In both situations, the terminology res- onated with the public, who were then moved to action. However, HEJN quickly moved from traditional protest strategies to more institutionalized forms of political participation, including lobbying the city council and the Connecticut state legislature on issues dealing with Connecticut’s landfills, closing the coal-burning power plants in the state, and reducing diesel school bus emissions in the state. Electoral Strategy During interviews, HEJN members elaborated on the organization’s pri- mary accomplishments. One of the group’s earliest electoral accomplish- ments was its role in the 1999 election of Elizabeth Horton Sheff to the Hartford City Council. Horton Sheff, an African-American woman, was a Green Party representative with a strong commitment to environmental jus- tice.9 Members of HEJN reported that they actively participated in her cam- paign and ultimate election. Horton Sheff has been extraordinarily responsive to the interests of HEJN. Lobbying for Policy Change Another accomplishment was the “asthma emergency” declared by the city council in 2000. Members of HEJN lobbied members of the city coun- cil for roughly three years prior to this declaration. The asthma emergency 38 Urban Affairs Review distribution. © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized at SUNY AT BUFFALO on August 27, 2007 http://uar.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://uar.sagepub.com Chambers / Minority Empowerment and Environmental Justice 39 has raised awareness of the problem and contributed to the commitment on the part of the city’s health department to improve environmental quality and public health with regard to respiratory illness (activist interview, February 15, 2002). The election of Horton Sheff solidified the passage of the asthma emergency because she cosponsored the resolution on the city council (Hall 2000). In addition to lobbying for the asthma emergency, HEJN lobbied the city health department to hire an environmental health educator. In response, according to activist interviews, the city did so in 2000. The creation of this position was a milestone because it was the first time that the city had des- ignated a specific individual to deal with the issue of environmental justice for the people of Hartford (Hartford’s Environmental Public Health Educator, interview, April 22, 2002). In interviews, all members of HEJN reported a good working relationship with this city employee. The environmental health educator has been very responsive to the community and worked with community members to gain more political power in the city (activist interview, February 21, 2002). In 2000, the organization also succeeded in convincing the city council to reject a proposal that would have allowed a medical waste facility to locate in the city. Had the facility opened, the company would have shred- ded medical waste and sterilized the remaining waste, something that would have been hazardous to the health of city residents (Mason 2000). The success in preventing this facility from opening was the result of protests at the offices of the company that wanted to open the waste facil- ity and lobbying efforts with the city council (activist interview, February 15, 2002). Interestingly, Horton Sheff, the newly elected city council member, played a key role in this decision. Members of HEJN provided her with the necessary research to persuade a majority on the city council to change their minds and vote against permitting the medical waste facility to locate in Hartford (president of HEJN, interview, June 27, 2006). Finally, one of the most recent accomplishments according to members and nonmembers of HEJN, was the city’s 2002 agreement to renegotiate their contract with CRRA. HEJN members lobbied since the inception of the group to amend the contract with the landfill operator. Ultimately, in 2002, they pressured the city council to renegotiate their 1982 contract with CRRA, a contract that previously included no expiration date, as well as a gag rule on city employees (elected and appointed), which prevented them from opposing CRRA facilities and services (activist interview, March 14, 2002; activist interview, March 18, 2002). distribution. © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized at SUNY AT BUFFALO on August 27, 2007 http://uar.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://uar.sagepub.com Statewide Focus The stability of the organization has allowed for it to expand its focus statewide. Efforts are now under way to improve environmental health in the state. The organization works effectively with the Connecticut legisla- ture and with bureaucratic agencies at the state and federal level, particu- larly the DEP and the U.S. Environmental Protection Agency (EPA). These activities are evidence that HEJN is an active and institutionalized player in the political and policy-making process. In partnership with activists from other Connecticut cities, HEJN is par- ticipating in the fight to shut down five power plants, known as the “filthy five,” located primarily in Connecticut’s poorest cities. During the time of this study, members of HEJN were lobbying state legislators around this issue and testifying at hearings about these power plants and the public health problems they cause. Another statewide issue, the campaign to reduce diesel emissions from school buses, is finally gaining momentum throughout Connecticut largely as a result of minority activists fighting for environmental justice in Hartford. The New England regional office of the EPA, the state Department of Health, and the Hartford Health Department are all persuaded that this is a pressing issue, at least in part because of HEJN’s lobbying and outreach (Connecticut’s Urban Program Manager, interview, April 22, 2002; Hartford Environmental Health Educator, inter- view, April 22, 2002). Organizational Strategy: A Formula for Effective and Sustained Mobilization Although HEJN has achieved some remarkable successes in the policy arena, perhaps its most important achievement to date has been the imple- mentation of an organizational strategy to overcome the substantial diffi- culties inherent in minority mobilization. The minority empowerment literature demonstrates that marginalized groups such as racial and ethnic minorities often experience numerous hurdles when trying to organize to influence the policy process (Bobo and Gilliam 1990; Browning, Marshall, and Tabb 1984, 2003; Eisinger 1982; Fung 2004). In the environmental context, Bullard (2000, 94) has observed that “the task of mobilizing local citizens on an environmental issue is enhanced when the community has the leadership, knowledge, tactical skills, and communication networks to challenge the system of domination, including giant corporations”. HEJN 40 Urban Affairs Review distribution. © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized at SUNY AT BUFFALO on August 27, 2007 http://uar.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://uar.sagepub.com demonstrates that effective organizational strategies can overcome a com- munity’s obstacles to facilitate mobilization. The following discussion identifies and examines HEJN’s key organizational strategies for mobiliz- ing a poor and undereducated minority constituency. Not only have these strategies led to mobilization of HEJN members, they have transformed the organization into a key stakeholder that has enjoyed significant successes in the policy-making arena. Racial/Ethnic Composition As noted in the minority empowerment and environmental justice litera- ture, racial/ethnic diversity is important for organizational success. HEJN was founded by minorities and continues to be minority led. Unlike many other multiethnic organizations, it has withstood changing organizational goals, and it attracts members from the greater Hartford area. The organiza- tion has succeeded in creating a multiracial and diverse membership base. For example, HEJN’s steering committee is 60% Black, 20% Latino, and 20% White. Seventy five percent of the steering committee members are also low-income individuals. Of the 50 people who regularly attend the organization’s monthly meetings, approximately 50% are White, 40% are Black, and 10% are Latino (president of HEJN, interview, December 10, 2004). Another important characteristic is the involvement of Whites in HEJN’s mostly minority coalition. Whites became involved for several rea- sons. First, traditional environmentalists are typically middle-class Whites who are broadly concerned with preservation of ecosystems and individual species, reduction of environmental harm caused by industrialization, and the protection of human health and aesthetic values. In contrast, environ- mental justice activists are concerned with discriminatory siting decisions that place an undue environmental burden on specific communities based on race, class, or some other distinguishing characteristic (Bullard 2000, 7).10 For some Whites who joined HEJN, the messages about environmental problems that disproportionately affected poor minorities in Hartford res- onated; thus they broadened their environmental activism beyond the tradi- tional sphere of the environmentalists. Other White members (reportedly the majority) are members of White suburban churches concerned about social justice (activist interview, February 15, 2002). HEJN’s goals and mission allow them to work locally on important issues related to social justice. For others, it is the fact that air quality is relevant to urban and suburban resi- dents. According to the work of Bullard, Rueben, and Johnson (2001), asthma and air quality are issues that make multiracial coalitions feasible Chambers / Minority Empowerment and Environmental Justice 41 distribution. © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized at SUNY AT BUFFALO on August 27, 2007 http://uar.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://uar.sagepub.com because the impact extends beyond poor and minority residential areas that are typically closer to pollution sources. Therefore, beyond broad environ- mental concerns and a commitment to social justice, White members have self-interest because pollution extends outside the city limits of Hartford. The guiding philosophy for HEJN is that as long as minorities remain the majority of the organization, minority members will have a sense of ownership and will help the organization flourish. Whereas firsthand expe- riences with environmental and health problems motivate many individuals to join HEJN, the organization strives to ensure that their participation will continue over the long term. As Dr. Mitchell explains: There is a formula that we use. One of the keys is that it [the organization] has to be minority led. It has to start off with a good minority base. And also, it has to have the staff resources. Low-income people generally need a lot more assistance with transportation, child care, with food. We opened a food bank here and we also have nice dinners at our monthly meetings. Some of the members tell me that the meal at the monthly meeting is the best meal their family has. We also arrange for child care during the meetings and for transportation. This is how we help to keep the organization minority based. (president of HEJN, interview, March 14, 2002). In contrast to HEJN’s strategies, a sister organization in New Haven, Connecticut emerged in 2001 as an attempt to spread the message about environmental justice statewide. A key difference is that the New Haven Branch was an existing organization that sought an affiliation with HEJN because of HEJN’s reputation as the leading environmental justice organi- zation in the state (president of HEJN, interview, June 27, 2006). Whereas the Hartford branch is minority founded and led, the New Haven organiza- tion was primarily middle class, White environmentalists; thus it has expe- rienced some noteworthy challenges. As Dr. Mitchell pointed out, The problem we’re having in New Haven is getting people of color to partic- ipate. It’s much easier to talk to people who already know about the issues. So, our base in New Haven is mainly middle-class Whites who belonged to other environmental organizations. When we started to point out urban issues, it was very easy for them to catch on and do the moving and shaking that needed to be done. We tried to form a minority-based group affiliated with the New Haven branch called “Concerned Parents for Environmental Justice.” We were only able to meet once a month and they needed a lot more educa- tion, support, practice, and guidance between meetings. We don’t have that kind of staff in New Haven and so that portion of the organization didn’t move forward (president of HEJN, interview, December 10, 2004). 42 Urban Affairs Review distribution. © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized at SUNY AT BUFFALO on August 27, 2007 http://uar.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://uar.sagepub.com Chambers / Minority Empowerment and Environmental Justice 43 Overall, Mitchell characterizes the New Haven branch as “not as friendly” to less educated, low-income people of color with limited access to technical information. Mitchell claims that because New Haven Branch members have constant access to technology (Internet), that they are far less patient regarding time-intensive training sessions. Many of the New Haven members conduct their own research and work independently (pres- ident of HEJN, interview, June 27, 2006). The Hartford Branch is able to attract members from the city and the surrounding suburbs, most of whom are White. Although there are exam- ples of multiracial groups focused on environmental justice, it is more common to find members living in the same neighborhood and forging multiracial coalitions based on a shared sense of discrimination (Checker 2001). HEJN is unique because the membership base is spread throughout the Greater Hartford area. Altogether, HEJN has been able to create a viable and stable multiracial organization. A support staff with the responsibility for general organiza- tion ensures that members’ needs are met so that they can participate con- sistently in the organization. These efforts enable HEJN to maintain its minority base and thus its permanence as an organization. Technical Training HEJN places great emphasis on the technical training and education of its members. This ongoing educational training is pursued by members and is critically important to the organization. Members are sophisticated in their understanding of the scientific aspects of environmental justice. This knowledge, along with their firsthand familiarity with environmental dis- parities, is a key component in their legitimacy among policy makers (Connecticut’s Urban Program Manager, interview, April 22, 2002). Despite the limited level of formal education among members, many members can thoroughly explain issues such as the effects of particulate matter from diesel emissions on respiratory illness, and the health impacts of dioxins and other toxic chemicals. As one member noted, Our people are very interested in learning very complex things, and they’ve been able to use their knowledge. At first the politicians wouldn’t listen to us at all. And then they’d say, “You’ve got these grandmothers talking this language that we don’t even understand so it must be something really important.” And whenever someone does research to find out if what we’re saying is true, they find out that it is true. And that’s very different from other groups. Members’ legitimacy and comfort are important. The politicians trust distribution. © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized at SUNY AT BUFFALO on August 27, 2007 http://uar.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://uar.sagepub.com 44 Urban Affairs Review what we say. It’s been amazing that people who are not even involved with our organization are getting our message and carrying it forward (activist interview, March 14, 2002). Knowledge regarding environmental pollutants and public health prob- lems enhances the ability of members to engage in highly organized commu- nity outreach. One HEJN member who represents a local parent organization in Hartford is a Jamaican immigrant. She explained: One of our greatest accomplishments is the level of education we have and our ability to educate the community on environmental issues (activist interview, February 22, 2002). HEJN members regularly conduct “Hartford Toxics Tours” for people in the community as a way of raising awareness about local sources of pollution. These tours include trips to solid waste incinerators, power plants, and landfills. The HEJN tour guides provide background informa- tion about each facility and how it affects the health of the community. The guides also discuss HEJN’s efforts to eliminate or clean up the facil- ities. An interesting characteristic of HEJN’s educational strategy is that members are instructed by the group’s president, Dr. Mitchell, and then teach others what they have learned. Dr. Mitchell is a public health physician who was trained at Johns Hopkins University. The fact that the group is self-reliant for its scientific education is distinctive. A different approach is followed by a Boston-based environmental justice organiza- tion, Alternatives for Community and Environment (ACE); that group, which is primarily focused on asthma prevention, forged a coalition with local universities for its scientific information (Brown et al. 2003). By contrast, HEJN had to develop its own group resources for technical and educational training. Interviews with HEJN activists indicate that in addition to the sophisti- cated technical knowledge possessed by many members, another factor in HEJN’s ability to accomplish its goals and appear credible to other stake- holders is the fact that several of its members have legal or political exper- tise. One of the founding members of the organization, Attorney Cynthia Jennings, is among the most active environmental justice attorneys in the state. Attorney Jennings was originally a member of ONE CHANE who decided to pursue a legal education to work for environmental justice (activist interview, February 22, 2002). Several suburban members of the organization have also provided political guidance to the group. According to one member, distribution. © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized at SUNY AT BUFFALO on August 27, 2007 http://uar.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://uar.sagepub.com Chambers / Minority Empowerment and Environmental Justice 45 We’ve been really fortunate because some of our White suburban members bring some political knowledge that’s very helpful. They’ve been wonderful about hanging back and letting members from Hartford take the lead (activist interview, February 15, 2002). According to members interviewed in this study, the scientific, legal, and political knowledge collectively possessed by members are key factors in the organization’s successes. In fact, it was reported in multiple interviews that the scientific knowledge that members possess has impressed policy makers, especially when members testify before the city council or the state legislature, and when they contact government agency stakeholders. The EPA has tagged HEJN as one of the two most active environmental justice organizations in New England (activist interview, March 14, 2002; Connecticut’s Urban Program Manager, interview, April 22, 2002). In inter- views, policy elites indicate that members are highly informed on public health matters. Their education has empowered them politically and pro- vided the skills to educate additional activists. From the successes at the local level noted earlier, to the move toward working on statewide initia- tives, to the recognition HEJN has received from government officials and organizations, there is considerable evidence that the organization is suc- ceeding in achieving substantive policy change and policies that are ulti- mately responsive to the minority community. In addition, as one HEJN member pointed out, For the most part, our members don’t have the money to make contributions to politicians. They aren’t friends with the governor. They don’t have the resources to hire lobbyists. But, they’ve learned how to work within the polit- ical system to get results. This is new for many members (activist interview, March 14, 2002). Given that environmental justice was not a major issue in Hartford prior to the early 1990s, the accomplishments since the inception of HEJN are considerable. Community Networking and Coalition Building A strategy HEJN employs is to reach out to preexisting nonenvironmental organizations, which is apparent in their extensive organizational member- ship list. Broadly centered on environmental justice concerns, HEJN unites approximately 30 grassroots, religious, and community organizations in distribution. © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized at SUNY AT BUFFALO on August 27, 2007 http://uar.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://uar.sagepub.com 46 Urban Affairs Review the city. To accomplish this, HEJN seeks out members of local organizations with a concern about environmental justice. As one member explained, We go and do outreach to other groups and instead of trying to snatch their leadership and take them from their organization to ours, we really look for the one person who may not be one of the most active leaders, but for whom asthma is a real touchstone. And we try to energize them at a higher level in their own organization through their action in ours (activist interview, February 15, 2002). The environmental representatives from the various community organi- zations regularly attend HEJN events. As Dr. Mitchell explained, “These environmental representatives are a source of direct communication between the member organizations and HEJN” (president of HEJN, interview, December 10, 2004). Interestingly, since the inception of HEJN, many of the member community organizations have created environmental positions on their boards of directors. Although there is no concrete evidence that HEJN is the cause of this trend, it is interesting that many of HEJN’s orga- nizations have created these posts after their members became involved with HEJN. The results of HEJN’s outreach efforts are apparent at their monthly meetings. Meetings begin with introductions of all those in attendance. During the time of this research project, meetings consistently included grassroots members of HEJN and representatives from 15 to 20 of its member organizations. The purpose of monthly meetings is to raise aware- ness of important environmental justice issues, to schedule subcommittee meetings, and to devise strategies to advance group interests. Many of Hartford’s senior citizens are the organization’s most active individual members. Many of these seniors are also members of grass- roots senior citizen organizations in Hartford. In addition, many other racially and ethnically based grassroots organizations are HEJN members. The Black church, a foundation of the civil rights movement, continues to be an important component of HEJN. However, the religious commu- nity in HEJN extends beyond the Black church, including members of several predominantly White suburban churches with highly educated members who have a commitment to environmental equality. Although White membership remains the minority of HEJN’s membership, the organization has achieved a level of success as a multiracial and multi- ethnic organization. distribution. © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized at SUNY AT BUFFALO on August 27, 2007 http://uar.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://uar.sagepub.com Chambers / Minority Empowerment and Environmental Justice 47 Leadership Development The importance of minority leadership has been documented in the minority politics literature (Tate 2004); however, the way to develop leaders remains an unanswered question. For communities of color, having repre- sentatives or leaders who share demographic experiences can contribute to political knowledge and greater satisfaction with their elected representa- tives (Tate 2004). As an African-American leader who shares similar pas- sions about social justice and the plight of minorities in Hartford, Mitchell embodies effective leadership. By using his scientific background, Mitchell educates HEJN members who use their newly acquired knowledge to become lay experts in their communities. One of HEJN’s long-standing goals is to empower members so that they may improve their local environment and increase opportunities in their own lives. Leadership training is a means to attain this goal. Monthly meet- ings serve as the primary place where this early leadership training begins. Members rotate as monthly meeting leaders, timekeepers, and reporters on the activities of member organizations and the government. This rotation of leadership has given members a wide range of leadership experience. Moreover, this has expanded members’ involvement in environmental jus- tice outside of the monthly meetings. In addition, the organization holds roughly five leadership development training sessions each year. Finally, the organization presents leadership awards to grassroots members who have shown exceptional leadership and commitment to the cause of envi- ronmental justice. Dr. Mitchell explained: Leadership development is something you really have to do in low-income communities. And it pays off. It’s amazing to see what these folks do once they’re empowered. They start going back to school, they start getting better jobs, doing things to continue to develop themselves and their children. (pres- ident of HEJN, interview, December 10, 2004). Bullard (2000) indicates that Black environmental justice activists often develop their decision-making skills in indigenous community institutions (94). Interestingly, HEJN is not reliant upon preexisting structures, such as other community organizations, for leadership. Rather, they take it upon themselves to train and cultivate a large and diverse group of members who have not acquired leadership skills elsewhere. Thus the organization uses a blend of leadership and technical training discussed earlier to improve the effectiveness of the organization itself and to expand opportunities for its members. In this way, they empower their own members to become the leaders within HEJN and other organizations. distribution. © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized at SUNY AT BUFFALO on August 27, 2007 http://uar.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://uar.sagepub.com Ongoing Challenges Even with evidence of policy responsiveness on the part of public officials, HEJN faces many of the challenges associated with nonprofit, community organizations. According to Dr. Mitchell, the organization struggles to find resources. Retaining a staff, offering training sessions, writing reports, writ- ing grants, and educating the public are resource intensive. The majority of the organization’s funding comes from regional and national foundations. However, many of the available funding sources do not fund controversial organizations such as HEJN, particularly those that challenge the actions of public sector entities. Limited resources pose challenges in the face of a myriad of new and recurring issues that emerge every few months, such as the new negotiation with the trash authority. Finally, Dr. Mitchell also contends that the organization does not do a very good job of publi- cizing their major accomplishments, which probably limits HEJN’s ability to raise funds. Despite these areas of weakness, the organization has man- aged to achieve a measure of success on the issues they do pursue (presi- dent of HEJN, interview, June 27, 2006). HEJN’s Place in the Minority Empowerment and Environmental Justice Literature The minority empowerment literature offers some instructive perspec- tives on the organizational strategies embraced by HEJN. This literature addresses the challenges minorities often face in the political process and possible ways to overcome these hurdles. Emphasis is placed rather nar- rowly on protest and electoral strategies to increase minority incorporation in policy making. In addition, the scholars in this field have not specifically addressed the prerequisites for sustaining such coalitions. HEJN is multira- cial, has remained active over time, and has focused on a number of differ- ent environmental justice and health-related issues. Examining HEJN also demonstrates how an organization can use federal policy to advance its interests. HEJN has capitalized on federal policies enacted by the Clinton Administration to strengthen its case for public health disparities. The organization has also succeeded in increasing demo- cratic participation by bringing previously underrepresented groups to the policy-making table. Beyond the idealistic goal of full participation in a democracy, there is evidence that this involvement reflects a permanent shift in political participation for members of HEJN. 48 Urban Affairs Review distribution. © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized at SUNY AT BUFFALO on August 27, 2007 http://uar.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://uar.sagepub.com Chambers / Minority Empowerment and Environmental Justice 49 Multiracial Coalition with Minority Leadership Much of the previous empirical research finds that multiracial coalitions are difficult to maintain over time (DeLeon 2003; Hero and Clarke 2003; Mollenkopf 2003; Orr 2003; Owens and Rich 2003; Perry 2003; Pinderhughes 2003). However, as Bullard, Warren, and Johnson (2001) have indicated, air quality and other health-related issues that extend beyond poor and minority communities might be the policy area that unites geographically separated and racially diverse communities over the long-term because in many cases pollution knows no boundaries. In many ways, the shared health risks across geographic areas are a key component in HEJN’s multiracial coalition. In other policy arenas such as poverty policy, it is more difficult to keep a diverse coalition together because the policy only has an effect on the less empowered members of the coalition. Therefore, long-term multiracial coali- tions may be uniquely feasible in the environmental justice arena because the public health consequences are shared widely. In turn, sustained mobilization of the group contributes to its perceived legitimacy. This is especially evident in news stories from the Hartford Courant. Articles in the city’s major paper not only cover the issues HEJN supports and their activities, but integrate members’ perspectives when covering any issue the organization has adopted. This can be seen as increasing the visibility of the organization and the perception that the organization is a legitimate actor in local politics. HEJN’s enduring coali- tion has also led to the perception among policy makers that the organiza- tion and its 30-plus member organizations are a permanent force in the local environmental policy-making process (Connecticut’s Urban Program Manager, interview, April 22, 2002; Hartford’s Environmental Public Health Educator, interview, April 22, 2002). The findings of this case study demonstrate that policy responsiveness can occur without significant levels of minority incorporation in the formal polit- ical structure. The coalition in this study did not seek to take control of the formal operations of government, but to help create public policy that addresses the concerns of the minority community. Essentially, HEJN has made considerable strides to transcend its status as a second-tier player in the political process despite the fact that it does not follow an electoral strategy. Federal Policy The importance of federal involvement in policies of interest to minori- ties is reflected in the experiences of HEJN. The organization has capital- ized on the federal environmental policies implemented under the Clinton distribution. © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized at SUNY AT BUFFALO on August 27, 2007 http://uar.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://uar.sagepub.com 50 Urban Affairs Review Administration such as Executive Order 12898 and the Urban Environmental Initiative (UEI). This executive order requires all federal agencies to include the achievement of environmental justice as a part of their mission. Essentially, it gave environmental justice activists the legal backing they long desired. In addition to the executive order, in 1995 the Clinton Administration also launched UEI under the EPA in Region 1, New England (Urban Environmental Program11). This program is aimed at improving environmental and public health in Hartford, Providence, and Boston by working cooperatively with community organizations. Although these new policies were not often mentioned in interviews for this study, it is evident that they contribute to state and local governmental attention to environmental justice. It also seems that the executive order and UEI have made the government more receptive to environmental justice. This has undoubtedly enhanced the legitimacy of its dealings with the government. Increasing Democratic Participation As the organizational umbrella for minority mobilization around envi- ronmental justice issues in Hartford, HEJN is the major vehicle for demo- cratic participation in this important policy area. The organizational strategies embraced by HEJN and its resulting policy achievements have brought underrepresented groups to the governmental decision-making table. HEJN has raised the awareness of public health issues in the city, which has clearly made the government more responsive and effective in this policy area. The strategic efforts of HEJN to move from protest to insti- tutionalized participation have successfully advanced its concerns. In terms of the environmental justice literature, this case study offers a template for how minorities can affect the urban environmental policy process. HEJN’s organizational formula of maintaining a multiracial organi- zation, encouraging the policy training of its members, building coalitions with existing community organizations, engaging in leadership training, hav- ing a dynamic and scientifically trained leader, and moving from protest activities to institutionalized participation in local politics all contribute to its stability and success. These organizational strategies have led to sustained and effective minority involvement in environmental justice policy. The template that HEJN presents for creating a sustainable multiracial organization that achieves policy responsiveness is particularly useful for racial and ethnic minorities fighting for environmental equality in urban America. Environmental justice activists would be wise to consider the fac- tors leading to environmental justice success in Hartford as measured by distribution. © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized at SUNY AT BUFFALO on August 27, 2007 http://uar.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://uar.sagepub.com Chambers / Minority Empowerment and Environmental Justice 51 responsive policy making. Beyond environmental justice, this study presents a new approach to analyzing the potential for multiracial coalitions. Although environmental concerns might be different from other policy areas because the environment can negatively affect people regardless of race, ethnicity, or class, this case study sheds light on the circumstances for sustainable minority coalitions, the importance of developing minority leaders to guarantee that minority interests will be top priority for the coali- tion, and demonstrates how federal policy can be used to advance coali- tional interests. Finally, this study demonstrates how multiracial coalitions like HEJN may increase democratic participation in our political system. Notes 1. The research for this paper includes a thorough review of local newspapers and in- depth interviews with 11 community activists with ongoing commitments to environmental justice in Hartford. Most, but not all, are members of HEJN. I selected respondents by identi- fying some of the most active environmental justice community leaders from newspaper arti- cles on the issue and through participant observation at HEJN monthly meetings. Respondents were asked to identify others who have been active over time and when an individual was men- tioned by more than one respondent I tried to interview that person. Participant observation is also incorporated in this study. From November of 2001 through November of 2003, I regu- larly attended monthly meetings with the Hartford Environmental Justice Network (HEJN), attended state legislative hearings with HEJN members, attended grassroots planning sessions, and participated in tours of toxic sites conducted by members of the organization. I also inter- viewed a representative from the Hartford Department of Health and a representative from the Environmental Protection Agency in New England in order to include the perspective of elite policy makers. 2. http://www.csde.state.ct.us/public/der/ssp/dist0102/dist041.pdf 3. I created Figure 1 by combining 2000 U.S. Census tract information and the location of municipal solid waste facilities and other point source pollutants. 4. ONE CHANE was created in 1988 when two neighborhood organizations merged into one organization. ONE CHANE members are some of the poorest residents with limited options for political power or mobility (Simmons 1994, 21). 5. CRRA recently lost $220 million dollars to Enron when that corporation declared bankruptcy. The contract with Enron stated that Enron would purchase power from CRRA for 10 years in exchange for $220 million from CRRA. 6. Interviews with community activists revealed that some people believe that there might still be some health problems with the landfill despite the fact that the odors are gone. 7. In 1998, Dr. Mitchell also created the Connecticut Coalition of environmental Justice in an effort to unite more organizations in the state with concerns about environmental justice. 8. The list of member organizations: Organizational Members of Hartford Environmental Justice Network, First Baptist Church of West Hartford, Black Men’s Society, Inc., Building Parent Power, Capitol Region Conference of Churches, Christian Activities Council, Coalition to Strengthen the Sheldon/Charter Oak Neighborhood (CSS/CON), Connecticut Citizen distribution. © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized at SUNY AT BUFFALO on August 27, 2007 http://uar.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://uar.sagepub.com 52 Urban Affairs Review Action Group, Connecticut College Holleran Center for Community Action, Connecticut Council on Occupational Safety and Health (ConnectiCOSH), Connecticut Public Interest Research Group (CONNPIRG), Ecological Health Organization (ECHO), Endometriosis Association, Fair Haven Management Team Environmental Subcommittee, The Green Party—Hartford, Hartford Areas Rally Together (HART), Hartford Federation of Teachers, Healthy Homes Program/Lead Safe Houses, Hispanic Health Council, Institute for Community Research, Men’s Club of Hartford, North Hartford Seniors in Action, Organized Northeasterners/ Clay Hill and North End (ONE-CHANE), First Presbyterian Church of Hartford, South Arsenal Neighborhood Development (SAND), South End Neighborhood Action Project (SNAP), South End NRZ of Hartford, South End Residents and Merchants Inc. of East Hartford, Sierra Club—Hartford, Toxics Action Center, Urban League of Greater Hartford, Vecinos Unidos, Warriors for Real Welfare Reform, and Working Lands Alliance—Hartford Food System. 9. Horton Sheff left the Green Party in 2003 and is now a Democratic member of the city council. 10. Environmental justice is also commonly referred to as environmental discrimination and environmental racism. 11. Urban Environmental Program. http://www.epa.gov/region1/eco/uep/11 (accessed 1May 2005). References Bailey, C., and C. E. Faupel. 1992. Environmentalism and Civil Rights in Sumter County, Alabama. In Race and the incidence of environmental hazards, edited by P. Mohai, and B. Bryant, 140–152. Boulder: Westview Press. Black, T., and J. A. Stewart. 2001. Burning and burying in Connecticut: Are regional solutions to solid waste disposal equitable? The New England Journal of Public Policy 16:15–34. Bobo, L. D., and F. D. Gilliam. 1990. Race, sociopolitical participation and Black empowerment. American Political Science Review 84:379–393. Brown, P., B. Mayer, S. Zavestoski, T. Webke, and J. Mandelbaum. 2003. The health politics of asthma: Environmental justice and collective illness experience in the United States. Social Science and Medicine 57:453–464. Browning, R. P., D. R. Marshall, and D. H. Tabb. 1984. Protest is not enough. Berkeley: University of California Books. ———, eds. 2003. Racial politics in American cities. 3rd ed. New York: Longman. Bullard, R. D., ed. 1993. Confronting environmental racism. Boston: South End Press. ———. 1994. Unequal protection. San Francisco: Sierra Club Books. ———. 2000. Dumping in Dixie. 3rd ed. Boulder: Westview Press. Bullard, R. D., and G. S. Johnson. 2000. Environmental justice: Grassroots activism and its impact on public policy decision making. Journal of Social Issues 56 (3): 555–578. Bullard, R. D., R. C. Warren, and G. S. Johnson. 2001. The quest for environmental justice. In Health issues in the Black community. 2d ed., edited by R. L. Braithwaite and S. E. Taylor, 471–488. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. Bullard, R. D., and B. H. Wright. 1987. Environmental racism and the politics of equity: Emergent trends in the Black community. Mid-American Review of Sociology 12 (2): 21–38. distribution. © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized at SUNY AT BUFFALO on August 27, 2007 http://uar.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://uar.sagepub.com Chambers / Minority Empowerment and Environmental Justice 53 Capek, S. 1993. The environmental justice frame: A conceptual discussion and an application. Social Problems 40:5–24. Checker, M. 2001. “Like Nixon coming to China”: Finding common ground in a multi-ethnic coalition for environmental justice. Anthropological Quarterly 74 (3): 135–146. CRJ: Commission for Racial Justice, United Church of Christ. 1987. Toxic wastes and race in the United States: A national report on the racial and socioeconomic characteristics of communities with hazardous waste sites. New York: United Church of Christ. DeLeon, R. 2003. San Francisco: The politics of race, land use, and ideology. In Racial poli- tics in American cities, 3rd ed., edited by R. P. Browning, D. R. Marshall, and D. H. Tabb, 167–196. New York: Longman. Eisinger, P. K. 1982. Black empowerment in municipal jobs: The impact of Black political power. American Political Science Review 76:380–392. Fung, A. 2004. Empowered participation. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univ. Press. Hall, L. 2000. Residents call for city action on asthma. Hartford Courant, June 7, p. B1. HEJN Mission Statement. http:/www.environmental-justice.org/11 May 2005. Hero, R. E., and S. E. Clarke. 2003. Latinos, Blacks, and multiethnic politics in Denver: Realigning power and influence in the struggle for equality. In Racial politics in American cities, 3rd ed., edited by R. P. Browning, D. R. Marshall, and D. H. Tabb, 309–328. New York: Longman. Jones, R. E. 1998. Black concern for the environment: Myth versus reality. Society and Natural Resources 11:209–228. Kuzyk, I. 2003. A Hartford primer and field guide. Hartford, CT: Trinity College. Mason, J. 2000. Group celebrates blocking of waste facility. Hartford Courant, February 11, p. B3. Myers, S. R. 2004. Public and environmental health concerns in the 21st century. Sustain: A Journal of Environmental and Sustainability Issues, Fall/Winter: 44–52. Moberg, M. 2001. Co-opting justice: transformation of a multiracial environmental coalition in southern Alabama. Human Organization 60 (2): 166–178. Mohai, P. 2003. African American concern for the environment. Environment 45 (5): 11–26. Mohai, P., and B. Bryant, eds. 1992. Race and the incidence of environmental hazards. Boulder: Westview Press. Mollenkopf, J. 2003. New York: Still the great anomaly. In Racial politics in American cities, 3rd ed., edited by R. P. Browning, D. R. Marshall, and D. H. Tabb, 115–139. New York: Longman. Orr, M. 2003. The struggle for Black empowerment in Baltimore. In Racial politics in American cities, 3rd ed., edited by R. P. Browning, D. R. Marshall, and D. H. Tabb, 255–274. New York: Longman. Owens, M. L., and W. J. Rich. 2003. Is strong incorporation enough? Black empowerment and the fate of Atlanta’s low-income Blacks. In Racial politics in American cities, 3rd ed., edited by R. P. Browning, D. R. Marshall, and D. H. Tabb, 199–224. New York: Longman. Perry, H. L. 2003. The evolution and impact of biracial coalitions and Black mayors in Birmingham and New Orleans. In Racial politics in American cities, 3rd ed., edited by R. P. Browning, D. R. Marshall, and D. H. Tabb, 227–252. New York: Longman. Pinderhughes, D. 2003. Chicago politics: Political incorporation and restoration. In Racial politics in American cities, 3rd ed., edited by R. P. Browning, D. R. Marshall, and D. H. Tabb, 143–163. New York: Longman. Simmons, L. B. 1994. Organizing in hard times. Philadelphia: Temple. Tate, K. 2004. Black faces in the mirror. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univ. Press. distribution. © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized at SUNY AT BUFFALO on August 27, 2007 http://uar.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://uar.sagepub.com Taylor, B. R. 1995. Ecological resistance movements. Albany: State Univ. of New York Press. Taylor, D. E. 1989. Blacks and the environment: Toward an explanation of the Concern and action gap between Blacks and Whites. Environment and Behavior 21 (2): 175–205. Walker, B., V. M. Mays, and R. Warren. 2004. The Changing landscape for the elimination of racial/ethnic health status disparities. Journal of Health Care for the Poor and Underserved 15:506–521. Wright, B. 1998. Endangered communities: The struggle for environmental justice in the Louisiana chemical corridor. Journal of Public Management and Social Policy 4 (2): 181–191. Zielbauer, P. 2002. Poverty in a land of plenty: Can Hartford ever recover. New York Times, August 26, p. A1. Stefanie Chambers is an associate professor at Trinity College in Hartford, Connecticut. She earned her PhD from Ohio State University in 1999. Her research interests include urban politics, environmental justice, urban education policy, and racial and ethnic politics. She is the author of Mayors and Schools: Minority Voices and Democratic Tensions in Urban Education, Temple University Press. Her research also appears in Political Science Quarterly, The New England Journal of Political Science, and Mayors in the Middle (Princeton University Press; Henig and Rich, eds.). 54 Urban Affairs Review distribution. © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized at SUNY AT BUFFALO on August 27, 2007 http://uar.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://uar.sagepub.com << /ASCII85EncodePages false /AllowTransparency false /AutoPositionEPSFiles true /AutoRotatePages /None /Binding /Left /CalGrayProfile (Dot Gain 20%) /CalRGBProfile (sRGB IEC61966-2.1) /CalCMYKProfile (U.S. Web Coated \050SWOP\051 v2) /sRGBProfile (sRGB IEC61966-2.1) /CannotEmbedFontPolicy /Error /CompatibilityLevel 1.3 /CompressObjects /Off /CompressPages true /ConvertImagesToIndexed true /PassThroughJPEGImages true /CreateJDFFile false /CreateJobTicket false /DefaultRenderingIntent /Default /DetectBlends true /ColorConversionStrategy /LeaveColorUnchanged /DoThumbnails false /EmbedAllFonts true /EmbedJobOptions true /DSCReportingLevel 0 /EmitDSCWarnings false /EndPage -1 /ImageMemory 1048576 /LockDistillerParams false /MaxSubsetPct 100 /Optimize false /OPM 1 /ParseDSCComments true /ParseDSCCommentsForDocInfo true /PreserveCopyPage true /PreserveEPSInfo true /PreserveHalftoneInfo false /PreserveOPIComments false /PreserveOverprintSettings true /StartPage 1 /SubsetFonts true /TransferFunctionInfo /Apply /UCRandBGInfo /Remove /UsePrologue false /ColorSettingsFile () /AlwaysEmbed [ true /ACaslon-Ornaments /AGaramond-BoldScaps /AGaramond-Italic /AGaramond-Regular /AGaramond-RomanScaps /AGaramond-Semibold /AGaramond-SemiboldItalic /AGar-Special /AkzidenzGroteskBE-Bold /AkzidenzGroteskBE-BoldIt /AkzidenzGroteskBE-It /AkzidenzGroteskBE-Light /AkzidenzGroteskBE-LightOsF /AkzidenzGroteskBE-Md /AkzidenzGroteskBE-MdIt /AkzidenzGroteskBE-Regular /AkzidenzGroteskBE-Super /AlbertusMT /AlbertusMT-Italic /AlbertusMT-Light /Aldine401BT-BoldA /Aldine401BT-BoldItalicA /Aldine401BT-ItalicA /Aldine401BT-RomanA /Aldine401BTSPL-RomanA /Aldine721BT-Bold /Aldine721BT-BoldItalic /Aldine721BT-Italic /Aldine721BT-Light /Aldine721BT-LightItalic /Aldine721BT-Roman /Aldus-Italic /Aldus-Roman /AlternateGothicNo2BT-Regular /Anna /AntiqueOlive-Bold /AntiqueOlive-Compact /AntiqueOlive-Italic /AntiqueOlive-Roman /Arcadia /Arcadia-A /Arkona-Medium /Arkona-Regular /AssemblyLightSSK /AvantGarde-Book /AvantGarde-BookOblique /AvantGarde-Demi /AvantGarde-DemiOblique /BakerSignetBT-Roman /BaskervilleBE-Italic /BaskervilleBE-Medium /BaskervilleBE-MediumItalic /BaskervilleBE-Regular /BaskervilleBook-Italic /BaskervilleBook-MedItalic /BaskervilleBook-Medium /BaskervilleBook-Regular /BaskervilleBT-Bold /BaskervilleBT-BoldItalic /BaskervilleBT-Italic /BaskervilleBT-Roman /BaskervilleMT /BaskervilleMT-Bold /BaskervilleMT-BoldItalic /BaskervilleMT-Italic /BaskervilleMT-SemiBold /BaskervilleMT-SemiBoldItalic /BaskervilleNo2BT-Bold /BaskervilleNo2BT-BoldItalic /BaskervilleNo2BT-Italic /BaskervilleNo2BT-Roman /Bauhaus-Bold /Bauhaus-Demi /Bauhaus-Heavy /BauhausITCbyBT-Bold /BauhausITCbyBT-Medium /Bauhaus-Light /Bauhaus-Medium /BellCentennial-Address /BellGothic-Black /BellGothic-Bold /Bell-GothicBoldItalicBT /BellGothicBT-Bold /BellGothicBT-Roman /BellGothic-Light /Bembo /Bembo-Bold /Bembo-BoldExpert /Bembo-BoldItalic /Bembo-BoldItalicExpert /Bembo-Expert /Bembo-ExtraBoldItalic /Bembo-Italic /Bembo-ItalicExpert /Bembo-Semibold /Bembo-SemiboldItalic /Berkeley-Black /Berkeley-BlackItalic /Berkeley-Bold /Berkeley-BoldItalic /Berkeley-Book /Berkeley-BookItalic /Berkeley-Italic /Berkeley-Medium /Berling-Bold /Berling-BoldItalic /Berling-Italic /Berling-Roman /BernhardModernBT-Bold /BernhardModernBT-BoldItalic /BernhardModernBT-Italic /BernhardModernBT-Roman /Bodoni /Bodoni-Bold /Bodoni-BoldItalic /Bodoni-Italic /Bodoni-Poster /Bodoni-PosterCompressed /Bookman-Demi /Bookman-DemiItalic /Bookman-Light /Bookman-LightItalic /Boton-Italic /Boton-Medium /Boton-MediumItalic /Boton-Regular /Boulevard /BremenBT-Black /BremenBT-Bold /CaflischScript-Bold /CaflischScript-Regular /Carta /Caslon224ITCbyBT-Bold /Caslon224ITCbyBT-BoldItalic /Caslon224ITCbyBT-Book /Caslon224ITCbyBT-BookItalic /Caslon540BT-Italic /Caslon540BT-Roman /CaslonBT-Bold /CaslonBT-BoldItalic /CaslonTwoTwentyFour-Black /CaslonTwoTwentyFour-BlackIt /CaslonTwoTwentyFour-Bold /CaslonTwoTwentyFour-BoldIt /CaslonTwoTwentyFour-Book /CaslonTwoTwentyFour-BookIt /CaslonTwoTwentyFour-Medium /CaslonTwoTwentyFour-MediumIt /CastleT-Bold /CastleT-Book /Caxton-Bold /Caxton-BoldItalic /Caxton-Book /Caxton-BookItalic /Caxton-Light /Caxton-LightItalic /CelestiaAntiqua-Ornaments /Centennial-BlackItalicOsF /Centennial-BlackOsF /Centennial-BoldItalicOsF /Centennial-BoldOsF /Centennial-ItalicOsF /Centennial-LightItalicOsF /Centennial-LightSC /Centennial-RomanSC /CenturyOldStyle-Bold /CenturyOldStyle-Italic /CenturyOldStyle-Regular /CheltenhamBT-Bold /CheltenhamBT-BoldItalic /CheltenhamBT-Italic /CheltenhamBT-Roman /Christiana-Bold /Christiana-BoldItalic /Christiana-Italic /Christiana-Medium /Christiana-MediumItalic /Christiana-Regular /Christiana-RegularExpert /Christiana-RegularSC /Clarendon /Clarendon-Bold /Clarendon-Light /ClassicalGaramondBT-Bold /ClassicalGaramondBT-BoldItalic /ClassicalGaramondBT-Italic /ClassicalGaramondBT-Roman /CMTI10 /CommonBullets /ConduitITC-Bold /ConduitITC-BoldItalic /ConduitITC-Light /ConduitITC-LightItalic /ConduitITC-Medium /ConduitITC-MediumItalic /CooperBlack /CooperBlack-Italic /CopperplateGothicBT-Bold /CopperplateGothicBT-BoldCond /CopperplateGothicBT-Heavy /CopperplateGothicBT-Roman /CopperplateGothicBT-RomanCond /Copperplate-ThirtyThreeBC /Copperplate-ThirtyTwoBC /Coronet-Regular /Courier /Courier-Bold /Courier-BoldOblique /Courier-Oblique /Critter /CS-Special-font /DextorD /DextorOutD /DidotLH-OrnamentsOne /DidotLH-OrnamentsTwo /DINEngschrift /DINEngschrift-Alternate /DINMittelschrift /DINMittelschrift-Alternate /DINNeuzeitGrotesk-BoldCond /DINNeuzeitGrotesk-Light /Dom-CasItalic /Dom-CasualBT /Ehrhard-Italic /Ehrhard-Regular /EhrhardSemi-Italic /EhrhardtMT /EhrhardtMT-Italic /EhrhardtMT-SemiBold /EhrhardtMT-SemiBoldItalic /EhrharSemi /ElectraLH-Bold /ElectraLH-BoldCursive /ElectraLH-Cursive /ElectraLH-Regular /EnglischeSchT-Bold /EnglischeSchT-Regu /ErasContour /ErasITCbyBT-Bold /ErasITCbyBT-Book /ErasITCbyBT-Demi /ErasITCbyBT-Light /ErasITCbyBT-Medium /ErasITCbyBT-Ultra /EUEX10 /EUFB10 /EUFB5 /EUFB7 /EUFM10 /EUFM5 /EUFM7 /EURB10 /EURB5 /EURB7 /EURM10 /EURM5 /EURM7 /EuropeanPi-Four /EuropeanPi-One /EuropeanPi-Three /EuropeanPi-Two /Eurostile /Eurostile-Bold /Eurostile-BoldExtendedTwo /Eurostile-ExtendedTwo /EUSB10 /EUSB5 /EUSB7 /EUSM10 /EUSM5 /EUSM7 /ExPonto-Regular /Fenice-Bold /Fenice-BoldOblique /FeniceITCbyBT-Bold /FeniceITCbyBT-BoldItalic /FeniceITCbyBT-Regular /FeniceITCbyBT-RegularItalic /Fenice-Light /Fenice-LightOblique /Fenice-Regular /Fenice-RegularOblique /Fenice-Ultra /Fenice-UltraOblique /FlashD-Ligh /Folio-Bold /Folio-BoldCondensed /Folio-ExtraBold /Folio-Light /Folio-Medium /FontanaNDEeOsF /FontanaNDEeOsF-Semibold /FormalScript421BT-Regular /Formata-Bold /Formata-MediumCondensed /FournierMT-Ornaments /FrakturBT-Regular /FranklinGothic-Book /FranklinGothic-BookItal /FranklinGothic-BookOblique /FranklinGothic-Condensed /FranklinGothic-Demi /FranklinGothic-DemiItal /FranklinGothic-DemiOblique /FranklinGothic-Heavy /FranklinGothic-HeavyItal /FranklinGothic-HeavyOblique /FranklinGothic-Medium /FranklinGothic-MediumItal /FranklinGothic-Roman /FrizQuadrataITCbyBT-Bold /FrizQuadrataITCbyBT-Roman /Frutiger-Black /Frutiger-BlackCn /Frutiger-BlackItalic /Frutiger-Bold /Frutiger-BoldCn /Frutiger-BoldItalic /Frutiger-Cn /Frutiger-ExtraBlackCn /Frutiger-Italic /Frutiger-Light /Frutiger-LightCn /Frutiger-LightItalic /Frutiger-Roman /Frutiger-UltraBlack /Futura /FuturaBlackBT-Regular /Futura-Bold /Futura-BoldOblique /Futura-Book /Futura-BookOblique /FuturaBT-Bold /FuturaBT-BoldCondensed /FuturaBT-BoldCondensedItalic /FuturaBT-BoldItalic /FuturaBT-Book /FuturaBT-BookItalic /FuturaBT-ExtraBlack /FuturaBT-ExtraBlackCondensed /FuturaBT-ExtraBlackCondItalic /FuturaBT-ExtraBlackItalic /FuturaBT-Heavy /FuturaBT-HeavyItalic /FuturaBT-Light /FuturaBT-LightCondensed /FuturaBT-LightItalic /FuturaBT-Medium /FuturaBT-MediumCondensed /FuturaBT-MediumItalic /Futura-ExtraBold /Futura-ExtraBoldOblique /Futura-Heavy /Futura-HeavyOblique /Futura-Light /Futura-LightOblique /Futura-Oblique /GalliardITCbyBT-Italic /GalliardITCbyBT-Roman /Garamond-Antiqua /Garamond-BoldCondensed /Garamond-BoldCondensedItalic /Garamond-BookCondensed /Garamond-BookCondensedItalic /Garamond-Halbfett /GaramondITCbyBT-Bold /GaramondITCbyBT-BoldCondensed /GaramondITCbyBT-BoldCondItalic /GaramondITCbyBT-BoldItalic /GaramondITCbyBT-BoldNarrow /GaramondITCbyBT-BoldNarrowItal /GaramondITCbyBT-Book /GaramondITCbyBT-BookCondensed /GaramondITCbyBT-BookCondItalic /GaramondITCbyBT-BookItalic /GaramondITCbyBT-Light /GaramondITCbyBT-LightCondensed /GaramondITCbyBT-LightCondItalic /GaramondITCbyBT-LightItalic /GaramondITCbyBT-LightNarrow /GaramondITCbyBT-LightNarrowItal /GaramondITCbyBT-Ultra /GaramondITCbyBT-UltraCondensed /GaramondITCbyBT-UltraCondItalic /GaramondITCbyBT-UltraItalic /Garamond-Kursiv /Garamond-KursivHalbfett /Garamond-LightCondensed /Garamond-LightCondensedItalic /GaramondThree /GaramondThree-Bold /GaramondThree-BoldItalic /GaramondThree-Italic /GaramondThreeSMSspl /GaramondThreespl /GaramondThreeSpl-Bold /GaramondThreeSpl-Italic /GarthGraphic /GarthGraphic-Black /GarthGraphic-Bold /GarthGraphic-BoldCondensed /GarthGraphic-BoldItalic /GarthGraphic-Condensed /GarthGraphic-ExtraBold /GarthGraphic-Italic /Geometric231BT-HeavyC /GeometricSlab712BT-BoldA /GeometricSlab712BT-ExtraBoldA /GeometricSlab712BT-LightA /GeometricSlab712BT-LightItalicA /GeometricSlab712BT-MediumA /GeometricSlab712BT-MediumItalA /Giddyup /Giddyup-Thangs /GillSans /GillSans-Bold /GillSans-BoldCondensed /GillSans-BoldItalic /GillSans-Condensed /GillSans-ExtraBold /GillSans-Italic /GillSans-Light /GillSans-LightItalic /GillSans-UltraBold /GillSans-UltraBoldCondensed /Gill-Special /Giovanni-Bold /Giovanni-BoldItalic /Giovanni-Book /Giovanni-BookItalic /Glypha /Glypha-Bold /Glypha-BoldOblique /Glypha-Oblique /Goudy /Goudy-Bold /Goudy-BoldItalic /Goudy-ExtraBold /Goudy-Italic /GoudyOldStyleBT-Bold /GoudyOldStyleBT-BoldItalic /GoudyOldStyleBT-ExtraBold /GoudyOldStyleBT-Italic /GoudyOldStyleBT-Roman /GoudySans-Bold /GoudySans-BoldItalic /GoudySansITCbyBT-Bold /GoudySansITCbyBT-BoldItalic /GoudySansITCbyBT-Medium /GoudySansITCbyBT-MediumItalic /GoudySans-Medium /GoudySans-MediumItalic /Granjon /Granjon-Bold /Granjon-BoldOsF /Granjon-Italic /Granjon-ItalicOsF /Granjon-SC /GreymantleMVB-Ornaments /Helvetica /Helvetica-Black /Helvetica-BlackOblique /Helvetica-Black-SemiBold /Helvetica-Bold /Helvetica-BoldOblique /Helvetica-Condensed /Helvetica-Condensed-Black /Helvetica-Condensed-BlackObl /Helvetica-Condensed-Bold /Helvetica-Condensed-BoldObl /Helvetica-Condensed-Light /Helvetica-Condensed-LightObl /Helvetica-Condensed-Oblique /Helvetica-Light /Helvetica-LightOblique /Helvetica-Narrow /Helvetica-Narrow-Bold /Helvetica-Narrow-BoldOblique /Helvetica-Narrow-Oblique /HelveticaNeue-BlackCond /HelveticaNeue-BlackCondObl /HelveticaNeue-Bold /HelveticaNeue-BoldCond /HelveticaNeue-BoldCondObl /HelveticaNeue-BoldExt /HelveticaNeue-BoldExtObl /HelveticaNeue-BoldItalic /HelveticaNeue-Condensed /HelveticaNeue-CondensedObl /HelveticaNeue-ExtBlackCond /HelveticaNeue-ExtBlackCondObl /HelveticaNeue-Extended /HelveticaNeue-ExtendedObl /HelveticaNeue-Heavy /HelveticaNeue-HeavyCond /HelveticaNeue-HeavyCondObl /HelveticaNeue-HeavyExt /HelveticaNeue-HeavyExtObl /HelveticaNeue-HeavyItalic /HelveticaNeue-Italic /HelveticaNeue-Light /HelveticaNeue-LightCond /HelveticaNeue-LightCondObl /HelveticaNeue-LightItalic /HelveticaNeueLTStd-Md /HelveticaNeueLTStd-MdIt /HelveticaNeue-Medium /HelveticaNeue-MediumCond /HelveticaNeue-MediumCondObl /HelveticaNeue-MediumExt /HelveticaNeue-MediumExtObl /HelveticaNeue-MediumItalic /HelveticaNeue-Roman /HelveticaNeue-ThinCond /HelveticaNeue-ThinCondObl /HelveticaNeue-UltraLigCond /HelveticaNeue-UltraLigCondObl /Helvetica-Oblique /HelvLight /Humanist521BT-Bold /Humanist521BT-BoldCondensed /Humanist521BT-BoldItalic /Humanist521BT-ExtraBold /Humanist521BT-Italic /Humanist521BT-Light /Humanist521BT-LightItalic /Humanist521BT-Roman /Humanist521BT-RomanCondensed /Humanist521BT-UltraBold /Humanist521BT-XtraBoldCondensed /Humanist777BT-BlackB /Humanist777BT-BlackItalicB /Humanist777BT-BoldB /Humanist777BT-BoldItalicB /Humanist777BT-ItalicB /Humanist777BT-LightB /Humanist777BT-LightItalicB /Humanist777BT-RomanB /ICMEX10 /ICMMI8 /ICMSY8 /ICMTT8 /ILASY8 /ILCMSS8 /ILCMSSB8 /ILCMSSI8 /Imago-Book /Imago-BookItalic /Imago-ExtraBold /Imago-ExtraBoldItalic /Imago-Medium /Imago-MediumItalic /Industria-Inline /Industria-InlineA /Industria-Solid /Industria-SolidA /Insignia /Insignia-A /IPAExtras /IPAHighLow /IPAKiel /IPAKielSeven /IPAsans /JoannaMT /JoannaMT-Bold /JoannaMT-BoldItalic /JoannaMT-Italic /KlangMT /Kuenstler480BT-Black /Kuenstler480BT-Bold /Kuenstler480BT-BoldItalic /Kuenstler480BT-Italic /Kuenstler480BT-Roman /KunstlerschreibschD-Bold /KunstlerschreibschD-Medi /Lapidary333BT-Black /Lapidary333BT-Bold /Lapidary333BT-BoldItalic /Lapidary333BT-Italic /Lapidary333BT-Roman /LASY10 /LASY5 /LASY6 /LASY7 /LASY8 /LASY9 /LASYB10 /LatinMT-Condensed /LCIRCLE10 /LCIRCLEW10 /LCMSS8 /LCMSSB8 /LCMSSI8 /LDecorationPi-One /LDecorationPi-Two /Leawood-Black /Leawood-BlackItalic /Leawood-Bold /Leawood-BoldItalic /Leawood-Book /Leawood-BookItalic /Leawood-Medium /Leawood-MediumItalic /LegacySans-Bold /LegacySans-BoldItalic /LegacySans-Book /LegacySans-BookItalic /LegacySans-Medium /LegacySans-MediumItalic /LegacySans-Ultra /LegacySerif-Bold /LegacySerif-BoldItalic /LegacySerif-Book /LegacySerif-BookItalic /LegacySerif-Medium /LegacySerif-MediumItalic /LegacySerif-Ultra /LetterGothic /LetterGothic-Bold /LetterGothic-BoldSlanted /LetterGothic-Slanted /Life-Bold /Life-Italic /Life-Roman /LINE10 /LINEW10 /Lithos-Black /Lithos-Regular /LOGO10 /LOGO8 /LOGO9 /LOGOBF10 /LOGOSL10 /LOMD-Normal /LubalinGraph-Book /LubalinGraph-BookOblique /LubalinGraph-Demi /LubalinGraph-DemiOblique /LucidaMath-Symbol /LydianBT-Bold /LydianBT-BoldItalic /LydianBT-Italic /LydianBT-Roman /LydianCursiveBT-Regular /Marigold /MathematicalPi-Five /MathematicalPi-Four /MathematicalPi-One /MathematicalPi-Six /MathematicalPi-Three /MathematicalPi-Two /Melior /Melior-Bold /Melior-BoldItalic /Melior-Italic /MercuriusCT-Black /MercuriusCT-BlackItalic /MercuriusCT-Light /MercuriusCT-LightItalic /MercuriusCT-Medium /MercuriusCT-MediumItalic /MercuriusMT-BoldScript /Meridien-Medium /Meridien-MediumItalic /Meridien-Roman /Minion-Black /Minion-Bold /Minion-BoldCondensed /Minion-BoldCondensedItalic /Minion-BoldItalic /Minion-Condensed /Minion-CondensedItalic /MinionExp-Italic /MinionExp-Semibold /MinionExp-SemiboldItalic /Minion-Italic /Minion-Ornaments /Minion-Regular /Minion-Semibold /Minion-SemiboldItalic /MonaLisa-Recut /MSAM10 /MSAM10A /MSAM5 /MSAM6 /MSAM7 /MSAM8 /MSAM9 /MSBM10 /MSBM10A /MSBM5 /MSBM6 /MSBM7 /MSBM8 /MSBM9 /MTEX /MTEXB /MTEXH /MTGU /MTGUB /MTMI /MTMIB /MTMIH /MTMS /MTMSB /MTMUB /MTMUH /MTSY /MTSYB /MTSYH /MTSYN /MusicalSymbols-Normal /Myriad-Bold /Myriad-BoldItalic /Myriad-CnBold /Myriad-CnBoldItalic /Myriad-CnItalic /Myriad-CnSemibold /Myriad-CnSemiboldItalic /Myriad-Condensed /Myriad-Italic /Myriad-Roman /Myriad-Sketch /Myriad-Tilt /NeuzeitS-Book ] /NeverEmbed [ true ] /AntiAliasColorImages false /DownsampleColorImages true /ColorImageDownsampleType /Bicubic /ColorImageResolution 300 /ColorImageDepth -1 /ColorImageDownsampleThreshold 1.50000 /EncodeColorImages true /ColorImageFilter /DCTEncode /AutoFilterColorImages true /ColorImageAutoFilterStrategy /JPEG /ColorACSImageDict << /QFactor 0.15 /HSamples [1 1 1 1] /VSamples [1 1 1 1] >> /ColorImageDict << /QFactor 0.15 /HSamples [1 1 1 1] /VSamples [1 1 1 1] >> /JPEG2000ColorACSImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 30 >> /JPEG2000ColorImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 30 >> /AntiAliasGrayImages false /DownsampleGrayImages true /GrayImageDownsampleType /Bicubic /GrayImageResolution 300 /GrayImageDepth -1 /GrayImageDownsampleThreshold 1.50000 /EncodeGrayImages true /GrayImageFilter /DCTEncode /AutoFilterGrayImages true /GrayImageAutoFilterStrategy /JPEG /GrayACSImageDict << /QFactor 0.15 /HSamples [1 1 1 1] /VSamples [1 1 1 1] >> /GrayImageDict << /QFactor 0.15 /HSamples [1 1 1 1] /VSamples [1 1 1 1] >> /JPEG2000GrayACSImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 30 >> /JPEG2000GrayImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 30 >> /AntiAliasMonoImages false /DownsampleMonoImages true /MonoImageDownsampleType /Bicubic /MonoImageResolution 1200 /MonoImageDepth -1 /MonoImageDownsampleThreshold 1.50000 /EncodeMonoImages true /MonoImageFilter /CCITTFaxEncode /MonoImageDict << /K -1 >> /AllowPSXObjects false /PDFX1aCheck false /PDFX3Check false /PDFXCompliantPDFOnly false /PDFXNoTrimBoxError true /PDFXTrimBoxToMediaBoxOffset [ 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 ] /PDFXSetBleedBoxToMediaBox false /PDFXBleedBoxToTrimBoxOffset [ 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 ] /PDFXOutputIntentProfile (U.S. Web Coated \050SWOP\051 v2) /PDFXOutputCondition () /PDFXRegistryName (http://www.color.org) /PDFXTrapped /Unknown /SyntheticBoldness 1.000000 /Description << /FRA /JPN /DEU /PTB /DAN /NLD /ESP /SUO /ITA /NOR /SVE /ENU >> >> setdistillerparams << /HWResolution [2400 2400] /PageSize [612.000 792.000] >> setpagedevice work_2hllexfjwnfnjgz2xxs3j2i7ri ---- S0022381613000170 506..519 Compliance Bias and Environmental (In)Justice David M. Konisky Georgetown University Christopher Reenock Florida State University Scholarship on race- and class-based disparities in regulatory outcomes has failed to provide a theoretically grounded account of this bias’ origin. We address this shortcoming by providing a microlevel explanation of how demographics influence compliance bias or the failure to detect noncompliant firms. We argue that regulatory compliance is best understood as a dual-agent—firm and regulatory officer—production function, and that community mobilization and agency decision-making authority shape bureaucrats’ incentives to report non- compliance. We test our argument with an original dataset on community mobilization and agency structure that delineates the political costs and benefits of state regulatory officers implementing the U.S. Clean Air Act. Using detection-controlled estimation, we find that while certain communities are vulnerable to compliance bias, such bias is mitigated in the presence of either politically mobilized communities or decentralized enforcement authority within the implementing agency. E qual protection under the law is a fundamental principle of democratic public policy. When governments fail to treat citizens equally, the very legitimacy of democracy is threatened.1 Accord- ingly, the roots of equal protection extend deeply and broadly in the discipline. Scholars recognize its impor- tance as a key component of the rule of law and the civil liberties protected in society (Maravall and Przeworski 2003). Bureaucracy scholars refer to doctrines of admin- istrative fairness and representation (Meier 1993) and judicial scholars to impartiality and neutrality (Raz 1977). The core questions on equal protection turn on whether government is treating citizens differently, and, if so, what remedies might reduce such inequities? In approaching this question, scholars have inves- tigated policy domains that are ripe for violations of equal protection such as housing, pay, environment, education, and employment. Of these areas, environ- mental protection is particularly salient because of the potential for adverse public health effects. Advocates for ‘‘environmental justice’’ often allege that minority and low-income communities experience dispropor- tionate environmental hazards, in part, as a result of unequal enforcement of laws (e.g., Bryant 1995; Bullard, 1993; Bullard & Johnson 2000). Some recent research investigating these claims has found that governments conduct fewer inspections and impose fewer punitive sanctions when firms are located in poor and minority areas, but other work has identified few such disparities (Dion, Lanoie & Laplante 1998; Gray and Shadbegian 2004; Helland 1998b; Konisky 2009; Konisky and Schario 2010; Scholz and Wang 2006). Notwithstanding the mixed results, these studies share a common approach of establishing correlations between community demographics and regulatory enforcement outputs. However, while demonstrating these correlations helps to diagnose the presence of enforcement bias, prior research has not developed a strong theoretical account of the sources of this bias. Enforcement actions rely upon initial determinations of firm compliance, which are generally ascertained through government detection efforts. As a result, ob- served correlations between community demographics and enforcement actions may be either evidence of bias originating in an agency’s decision to take that action or evidence of bias originating in the initial compliance determination. Moreover, bias in regulatory outputs is generated from a process that involves the strategic interaction of both firms and regulatory officers. The Journal of Politics, Vol. 75, No. 2, April 2013, Pp. 506–519 doi:10.1017/S0022381613000170 � Southern Political Science Association, 2013 ISSN 0022-3816 1 An online appendix for this article is available at http://journals.cambridge.org/jop containing supplemental analyses. Data and supporting materials necessary to reproduce the numerical results in the article will be made available at http://mailer.fsu.edu/ ;creenock/ by January 2013. 506 Observed correlations between community demo- graphics and regulatory outputs may reflect a firm’s decision to be compliant, an officer’s decision to accurately identify noncompliant firms, or both. When studying regulatory outputs alone, these sources of bias are observationally equivalent. We believe a more productive path for revealing the sources of bias is to focus on compliance. Com- pliance is the foundation upon which other regulatory outputs are based, and for this reason, studying firm compliance is not vulnerable to the first problem noted above. In this sense, exploring environmental justice issues within a compliance framework high- lights the core process within which we believe bias is likely to originally arise.2 Second, while compliance does entail dual-agent (firm and officer) production, we can explicitly model each data-generating process, allowing us to determine if the bias originates with firms and/or regulators. In this article, we develop a novel theoretical account of compliance bias, or the systematic non- detection of violations, in the context of environmental justice. Building on past work (e.g., Feinstein 1990; Helland 1998a, 1998b; Scholz and Wang 2006), we argue that compliance bias is best characterized as a dual-agent production function of firms and regulatory officers. While pursuing different goals, both firms and bureaucrats attempt to minimize their costs. We argue that the costs associated with noncompliance (firms) and failure to detect noncompliance (bureaucrats) are lower in poor and minority communities because these communities have fewer resources with which to document and protest noncompliance. For this reason, firms in these areas are more likely to be noncompliant and less likely to be detected by regulatory officers. This dual-agent approach reveals two potential remedies for such bias. First, politically mobilized communities are better equipped to generate compli- ance costs for firms and political costs for bureaucrats, and, as a result, bias will diminish in poor and minority communities that have overcome the collective action problems necessary to exert political pressure. Second, we argue that high-level agency managers have a strong incentive to overreport compliance rates in order to craft positive impressions of agency performance. For this reason, they are more likely to engage in what we refer to as motivated, nondetection of compliance when a firm is located in a poor or minority area, since these communities have fewer political resources and are therefore less likely to discover the bureaucrat’s behavior. The empirical setting for our analysis is firm-level compliance with the federal Clean Air Act (CAA). Using an original dataset on both local mobilization and the decision-making authority of the state regu- latory officers largely responsible for implementing the CAA, we employ detection-controlled estimation (DCE) to model the effects of demographic character- istics on both individual firm and regulatory officer compliance decisions. We find that compliance bias is more likely in Hispanic (but, not in African American) communities, but that such bias is mitigated in the presence of either politically mobilized communities or decentralized enforcement authority. Our results sug- gest that compliance bias in policy implementation can be curbed not just by investing in the political capacity of communities but also by modifying agency decision- making structures. The article proceeds as follows. We begin by developing our theoretical expectations about the link- age between compliance bias and community demo- graphics. We then discuss our research design and explain the usefulness of using a DCE approach to test these expectations. Next we discuss our empirical analysis of compliance bias in the case of enforcement of the CAA and then conclude with a discussion of the implications. Theory and Hypotheses Models of regulatory compliance recognize two distinct processes: Firms make decisions over compliance, and regulatory officers make decisions over compliance determination. Strategic-deterrence models provide ba- sic expectations that are useful for our purposes. In such models, firms and bureaucrats base their behavior on an expected utility calculation in which each attempts to maximize their expected payoffs given their beliefs about the other’s action (Braithwaite and Makkai 1991; Scholz 1991; Winter and May 2001). Of the many outcomes of this strategic interaction, we are interested in features of the policy environment that may increase the potential for ‘‘opportunistic’’ behavior—that is, when firms pursue noncompliance based on their lower expectations of being caught and/or punished by regulatory officers. The end result of this outcome is undetected noncompliance—the object of our study. We assume that firms choose whether to remain in compliance or to violate the law. In making this choice, firms are interested in maximizing their individual profit at the lowest cost of compliance. 2 A few studies look at disparities in firm compliance with mixed findings (Earnhart 2004a, 2004b; Mennis 2005; Scholz and Wang 2006). compliance bias and environmental (in)justice 507 The expected costs of compliance are related to various features of the market and to policy and political factors that shape the consequences of noncompliant behavior. Expectations about the costs of compliance are also related to the detection efforts pursued by regulatory officers, and specifically, the likelihood that noncompliant behavior will not only be discovered but treated as violations. It is for this reason that one needs to conceptualize compliance outcomes as a dual-agent production function. When firms expect agency offi- cials to pursue less rigorous enforcement strategies, they have greater incentive to avoid full compliance. Alternatively, when firms believe that agency officials are more likely to pursue a maximal deterrence strategy, they will have greater incentive to stay in compliance. We assume that bureaucrats choose whether to determine a given firm’s compliance status. This deci- sion is perhaps the most fundamental enforcement activity for a regulatory officer, since it is not only the first action in a long line of potential actions directed at an individual firm but also represents an important performance indicator for an agency at the aggregate level. In making this choice, officers are interested in maximizing the political benefits of successful detection (i.e., getting credit for making correct compliance determinations) while minimizing the political costs of errors (i.e., getting blamed for making incorrect com- pliance determinations). Political benefits stem from being responsive to policy demands such as managing the aggregate consequences of noncompliance (e.g., pollution levels, accident rates) and political demands including the preferences of political principals and other stakeholders. As we argue below, an important element in being responsive is whether the agency is viewed as being ‘‘effective.’’ In addition to the various types of transaction costs involved for any given case (i.e., search and information costs, bargaining and decision costs, policing and enforcement costs), regu- latory officers must also consider the political costs of their decisions. Specifically they must weigh the con- sequences of making wrong decisions, and we argue that they will allocate their effort to minimize the net costs of different incorrect compliance determinations. Incorrect compliance decisions come in two forms. First, the officer could wrongly attempt detec- tion of a compliant firm (so called ‘‘harassment’’; Scholz 1991). Second, the officer could fail to detect a noncompliant firm. Each of these errors generates different political costs from unique clientele. For the first error, business interests are more likely to gen- erate costs for officers, while environmental advocacy groups are more likely to generate costs for the second error. In the aggregate, at the level of a region or a community, officers attempting to minimize one set of errors necessarily increase the probability of the other (this is of course not the case at the individual firm level). On the whole, clientele generate cross-cutting incentives for officers, who attempt to minimize costs associated with making errors, offering officers a trade- off. A rational regulatory officer, seeking to be respon- sive to stakeholders, will attempt to minimize costs generated from relevant clientele. We are interested in how community demographics affect the second type of errors, or failures to detect noncompliance. As we will argue below, factors such as demographics alter the relative political costs of these errors, making one error more attractive than the other, ceteris paribus. In the context of firm compliance, officers are unable to fully and regularly assess the behavior of all regulated entities. Even if bureaucrats are motivated primarily by functional or intrinsic preferences (Brehm and Gates 1997), they are still constrained by practical limits. For this reason, bureaucrats may engage in some satisficing behavior as a decision-making shortcut (Simon 1976) or, alternatively, choose to strategically allocate more effort to accurately determine the com- pliance status of some firms more than others. This could take the form of directing agency efforts to easier cases (Wilson 1989) or directing resources to cases depending on the estimation of the political costs of a wrong decision. We assume that firms are aware that officers face such limitations but are uncertain of precisely which officer type they are dealing with—one preferring less or more rigorous detection effort. Given that firms and regulatory officers are un- certain about each other’s preferences, they develop beliefs using signals in the policy environment. These signals inform a firm’s (agency’s) expectations about an agency’s (firm’s) strategy, and they originate from political and policy task factors alike (Potoski 1999; Ringquist 1993; Scholz and Wei 1986; Scholz, Twombly and Headrick 1991; Wood 1992). When signals from the policy environment are sufficiently suggestive that regulatory officers may pursue less rigorous detection, firms will be more likely to risk noncompliance. Community Demographics, Mobilization, and Enforcement Authority We posit that community characteristics shape firms’ and regulatory officers’ behavior by providing signals about each others’ preferences over compliance and en- forcement, respectively. For firms, demographics pro- vide informative signals about the expected costs of compliance. For reasons we specify below, bureaucrats are less likely to devote their limited resources to 508 david m. konisky and christopher reenock correctly detecting noncompliance when the firms are located in less politically active areas. Because large minority and poor communities tend to have fewer political resources with which to engage in advocacy, these communities as well as the regulatory officers who serve them will be less likely to employ aggressive detection efforts. Strategic firms respond accordingly and should be more inclined to risk noncompliance, leading to our first hypothesis: H1: Firms in minority (or poor) neighborhoods are more likely to be in noncompliance. Community demographics may generate costs for regulatory officers in several ways. First, failure to detect noncompliance, if uncovered, can lead to objections from interested stakeholders. Rational bureaucrats seek- ing to minimize costs generated from a specific clientele over incorrect decisions will devote fewer resources to carefully determining compliance for cases where the costs associated with wrongful detections are lower. Conversely, they will dedicate more attention to those cases where the costs of making incorrect decisions are higher. To be clear, officers cannot simply ignore these resource-intense cases to avoid the costs associated with them. Doing so will generate either undetected non- compliance or detection against compliant firms, both of which generate costs, albeit from different clientele. In this sense, the costs that a regulator faces for failing to detect a noncompliant firm vary, depending on the probability that an incorrect determination will be re- vealed. Community characteristics enter this decision- making equation because some communities have better capacity to identify and dispute an incorrect compliance decision. In particular, poor and minority communities tend to have fewer political resources to demand and secure accurate compliance decisions from bureaucrats. This raises the relative attractiveness of compliance bias in these communities. A second reason regards the identification of potential violations. In policy contexts where third- party monitoring assists bureaucrats in detecting problems, communities with reserve time, resources, and social capital are better equipped to serve in this role. Poor and minority communities are less likely to possess this capacity. As a result, regulatory officers are more likely to mischaracterize noncompliant firms as compliant in these areas. Whichever reason holds, the end result is the same—poor and minority neighborhoods are less likely to be able to generate political costs for regulatory officers. Therefore, bureaucrats have less incentive to actively pursue noncompliant firms in these communities, leading to the following hypothesis: H2: Bureaucrats are less likely to code violating firms as noncompliant when they are located in minority (or poor) communities. The effect of community demographics on firm and regulatory officer behavior, however, should not be constant across all contexts. Rather, we argue that the effect should be mediated by two contextual features— the ability of a community to generate political costs through effective mobilization and the vulnerability of a regulatory officer to these costs. We discuss each in turn. Community Mobilization. Past work demonstrates that communities with higher political capacity are better able to influence firm decision making (Hamilton 1993, 1995; Hamilton and Viscusi 1999), and we argue that a similar dynamic exists with firm compliance. While community demographics provide signals to bureaucrats (and firms) about potential political mobilization, they do not account for the effects of actual mobilization. Politically mobilized communities should alter the incentives of firms and bureaucrats in decisions regarding compliance. Regard- ing firms, communities that overcome collective action problems and exercise their political voice can modify the costs of compliance through direct pressure, ‘‘sham- ing’’ poor performers, or litigation. Well-organized communities should also increase the political costs to a bureaucrat of making an incorrect decision, since they can protest and publicize what they believe are any erroneous decisions. In turn, these higher costs should reduce the likelihood of officers wrongly classifying a firm violating the law as compliant and of firms being noncompliant. Two specific political-mobilization hy- potheses follow from this logic: H3a: Firms in minority (or poor) communities are less likely to be noncompliant when they are located in politically mobilized communities. H3b: Bureaucrats are more likely to code violating firms in minority (or poor) communities as noncom- pliant when these communities are politically mobilized. Enforcement Authority. To this point, we have implic- itly assumed that all bureaucrats share similar incentive structures when it comes to determining firm compli- ance. Yet, within an agency, different bureaucrats have varied tasks. Front-line agents focus on the day-to-day activities of policy delivery, while high-level managers focus on achieving overall organizational goals and managing relationships with external stakeholders (Hammond 1986). As a consequence, the incentives that influence bureaucrats’ compliance decisions may vary with their position in the agency. Critically important for our purposes, not all states assign the compliance bias and environmental (in)justice 509 same personnel final decisionmaking authority over compliance decisions. Some states allow field officers wide discretion over compliance decisions, while others require final authorization from higher-level agency managers. We argue that there is strong reason to believe that, depending upon their position and task responsibilities, bureaucrats are not equally vulnerable to the political costs that a community may generate. Specifically, we posit that compared to lower-level field officers (e.g., career civil servant front-line com- pliance officers), higher-level bureaucrats serving in agency management roles (e.g., Department Secretaries, Deputy Secretaries, Division Managers, or Regional Directors) have additional incentives to inaccurately characterize noncompliant firms as compliant. Com- pliance rates are a key indicator by which stakeholders evaluate the performance of regulatory agencies, and they are often included in annual reports to state leg- islatures and to federal overseers. In many areas of policy, where it is difficult to precisely measure bureau- cratic performance, for reasons of both asymmetric information and causal ambiguity between agency action and policy outcomes, stakeholders rely on these types of metrics instead. The use of such performance indicators often results in goal displacement where agencies focus on producing metrics to satisfy external stakeholders, rather than achieving more relevant policy outcomes (Blau and Meyer 1971; Bohte and Meier 2000; Downs 1967). Knowing this, bureaucrats serving in high-level management positions responsible for crafting impressions of agency performance have a stronger incentive to deliver high compliance rates. High-level managers, faced with these incentives, may be tempted to overlook noncompliant firms in some circumstances. We refer to this behavior as motivated, nondetection of compliance, and it is analo- gous to Bohte and Meier’s (2000) idea of organizational cheating in public agencies. Although bureaucrats enjoy informational advantages over many stakeholders, there are potentially adverse consequences to engaging in this behavior, and strategic bureaucrats are more likely to pursue motivated, nondetection of compliance when the risks of being caught are smaller.3 It is here again that we return to the important role of community characteristics. Since there is a higher probability of the deception not being detected, bureaucrats will be more likely to deliberately mischaracterize a firm violating the law as compliant when the community in which the firm is located has fewer political resources (i.e., poor and minority communities). To be clear, this incentive is above and beyond the reasons stated previously regarding the political mobilization capacity of these communities, leading us to our final hypothesis: H4: Bureaucrats who are more likely to be held accountable for agency performance are more likely to mischaracterize violating firms as compliant when these firms are located in minority (or poor) communities. Research Design To test our expectations we employ DCE, a statistical technique that enables us to jointly model the dual production of compliance. Originally developed by Feinstein (1990), DCE statistically controls for the possibility that some portion of noncompliant firms may remain undiscovered by regulatory officers. As a result, facilities may be entered into a database as compliant when they are actually violating the law. DCE estimates the likelihood of a firm being non- compliant, as well as the likelihood that a given entity was correctly coded as noncompliant by a regulatory officer. Failure to account for the two reasons for observing compliance (actual compliance and the failure to detect noncompliance), which is implicitly done when compliance is modeled with a single-equation probit or logistic regression specification, can bias inferences. DCE techniques have been utilized to correct for compliance bias in a variety of settings, including taxpayer compliance (Feinstein 1999) and firm com- pliance with environmental (Brehm and Hamilton 1996; Helland 1998a, 1998b; Scholz and Wang 2006), occupational health and safety, (Feinstein 1990), and food and drug (Olson 1995) regulation. The DCE approach has two specific benefits for our purposes. First, it corrects for bias in estimating demographic effects in firm-compliance models. Second, it enables us to explicitly account for the dual-agent production problem. With DCE we can consider the sources of bias by separately testing whether demographics affect firm decisions on compliance and regulators’ determinations of facility compliance. Specifically, we utilize Feinstein’s (1990) DCE estimator, which consists of two binary choice models: one that models the likelihood of a ‘‘true’’ violation and a second that models the likelihood of detection of ‘‘true’’ compliance. Because the likelihood of a viola- tion and the likelihood of detection are separately unobservable, these likelihood functions are estimated 3To be clear, the mechanisms by which motivated nondetection occur are not necessarily nefarious. We do not necessarily envision managers explicitly manipulating compliance documents or turn- ing the other way to blatant violations—although we do not rule this out. Rather, such motivations may translate into directing subordinates’ detection efforts either to or away from specific geographical areas of concern, based upon political demands. 510 david m. konisky and christopher reenock jointly via maximum-likelihood estimation. The DCE estimator is equivalent to a bivariate probit model with partial observability (Abowd and Farber 1982; Poirier 1980). More formally, we model the observed dichotomous compliance variable, zi, as the product of two unobserved latent dichotomous variables, yi1 and yi2, such that zi is only observed, where zi 5 yi1 X yi2. In our application, we assign the interpretations of firm noncompliance and agency detection to yi1 and yi2, respectively, such that: Zi ¼ 1; yi1 and yi2 ¼1 0; otherwise n Thus, we expect to observe a firm being listed as noncompliant (zi 5 1) when both the firm is non- compliant and the agency has detected this noncom- pliance. In all other combinations of firm and agency behavior, we observe a case of compliance (zi 5 0), which highlights the fact that we cannot distinguish between true compliance and undetected violators.4 In this model the probabilities are jointly and simulta- neously determined with a correlated error term, r, Pr z ¼ 1ð Þ¼ F2 x1b1; x2b2; rð Þ Pr z ¼ 0ð Þ¼ 1 � F2 x1b1; x2b2; rð Þ yielding the following likelihood to be estimated: lnL ¼+N i¼1fzilnF2ðx1b1; x2b2; rÞ þ ð1 � ziÞ ln½1 � F2ðx1b1; x2b2; rÞ�g Identification of this model requires an exclusion of at least one exogenous variable to ensure that the parameters being estimated in each model are not identical. Moreover, identification is enhanced when the exogenous variable exhibits sufficient variation over the sample. This condition is likely to be met when the exogenous variable is continuous (Poirier 1980). In our model, Signature Authority (which as we describe below is our measure of agency structure) is a continuous exogenous variable which we restrict to the detection equation based on our theoretical argument that the location of decision making in a state administrative agency creates different incentives for bureaucrats. We do not include Signature Authority in the firm model given what we think is a reasonable assumption that firms are largely unaware of this feature of administrative agencies, and, even if they were aware, it is unlikely to affect their compliance costs. The other variables not included in both equations are the firm-level indicators of past enforce- ment. Because firms’ compliance costs are affected by the temptation to cheat, which is in turn a function of the likelihood of getting caught, we include measures of past government inspections in the firm equation. For their part, we argue that regulators will devote their time and effort to ‘‘bad actors,’’ so we include measures of whether recent violations resulted in a punitive action in the detection equation. The empirical setting for our analysis is the regulatory compliance of individual firms within the context of air pollution control across the U.S. states. We use an original dataset that combines firm- level compliance with the federal CAA with data on community characteristics and contextual variables across county, state administrative region, and U.S. states. The federal government sets most standards under the CAA, but the states have responsibility for enforcing many of its provisions. To best capture the policy and political demands on state regulatory officers, we use novel data on how each state agency divides enforcement responsibilities among bureau- crats internal to the agency. We discuss these data in greater detail below. Our attention to the details of administrative program structure does, however, generate a trade-off. Given the demands of gathering these data, we can only examine a limited time frame (2001–2004) for which we have compiled administra- tive data. However, we do not believe that this trade- off compromises our ability to draw valid inferences because our hypotheses only require cross-sectional variance. Moreover, by limiting our analysis to a single Presidential term, we can hold constant variations in national factors that might influence state enforcement patterns. Of course, we must be cautious extending our inferences beyond this temporal domain. Measuring Compliance The dependent variable, HPV Status, reflects whether a regulated facility was designated as a High Priority Violator (HPV) of the CAA. An HPV facility is one that is failing to meet core CAA obligations, usually pollu- tion performance standards. Dissimilar to minor paper- work violations, noncompliance of this sort can trigger significant punitive sanctions including substantial monetary penalties. For this reason, designating a firm as HPV is of high political relevance for regulatory officers. HPV Status is a dichotomous variable that takes a value of one for a facility designated as a HPV at any time during the year, and zero otherwise. The variable is 4It is possible that there could be ‘‘false’’ noncompliance, but this would be exceedingly rare in our context. HPV determinations represent cases of severe noncompliance and typically include major infractions of emissions standards, minimizing errors, even by overly zealous regulators. compliance bias and environmental (in)justice 511 measured on annual basis from 2001 to 2004, and we examine all federally reportable facilities under the CAA. The result is a panel dataset that includes a total of 160,896 cases (40,224 firms per year),5 although the number of cases analyzed is slightly fewer due to missing data.6 Table A.1 in the online appendix includes sources and descriptive statistics for all data. Measuring Community Characteristics Environmental justice concerns typically emerge with respect to race and class. We use two standard measures in the literature to assess the racial compo- sition of a community: Percentage of African-American Population and Percentage of Hispanic Population. The literature is less consistent when accounting for class, with most using some combination of income, pov- erty, and education measures. Rather than emphasize any one measure, we constructed a scale based on four standardized variables, median household income, percent below poverty line, percent college educated, and percent high school educated, each measured at the zip-code level. The resulting scale, Class, obtained a Cronbach’s alpha of .86, and an investigation of the dimensionality of the scale revealed a single factor with an eigenvalue of 2.73, accounting for 79% of the total variance. Measuring Community Political Mobilization To assess the degree of community political mobiliza- tion, we require a measure that captures whether citizens have overcome collective action costs and organized around environmental justice concerns. Standard meas- ures of political mobilization, such as voter turnout and campaign donations, are too broad to capture our concept of interest. Moreover, it is likely that it is precisely in communities where traditional political mobilization is low that the pressures for organization around equity issues are highest. As a result, we use a more direct measure: the presence of locally oriented environmental justice advocacy organizations. We assembled data from the People of Color Environmental Groups Directory (Environmental Justice Resource Center 2000), which publishes a list of organizations whose activities include advocating for environmental justice. Specifically, we coded the presence of groups listed as ‘‘environmental justice resource groups’’ at the zip-code level, as well as information about the constituency served by each group and its geographic focus. Using these data, we first aggregated this group information up to the three-digit zip-code level to take into account the positive spillovers from the presence of a group, under what we believe is a reasonable assumption that the reach of these groups extends beyond the specific mailing zip code of their main office.7 We then constructed a scale based on five standardized varia- bles, the total number of groups, the total number of groups focused on African Americans, the total number of groups focused on Hispanic groups, the total number of groups with a neighborhood focus, and the total number of groups with a local focus. The resulting scale, Mobilization, obtained a Cronbach’s alpha of .80, and an investigation of the dimensionality of the scale revealed a single factor with an eigenvalue of 2.54, which accounts for 92% of the total variance. Section 3 of the online appendix discusses the meas- urement of this variable in more detail. Measuring Regulatory Officer Incentives To test our hypothesis regarding motivated, nondetec- tion of compliance, we must know whether the author- ity to issue enforcement-related actions rests with field officers, is centralized in the hands of high-level agency officials, or lies somewhere in between. We believe that a reasonable proxy is the location within the agency where (or more precisely within whose hands) final signature authority to issue enforcement actions lies. We measure the locational authority over three sets of enforcement actions (Reenock and Gerber 2008). For each state air-pollution control agency, this measure divides (Final Authority—1) by (Vertical Depth—1), where Final Authority represents the location of final signature authority for a given action within the chain of command, and Vertical Depth represents the number of entities in the direct chain of command from the field officer up to and including the individual or committee at the top of the chain of command. Tennessee, for example, has a very centralized authority structure. Typically, enforcement actions are pushed up the agency’s chain of command all the way to the top, 5We correct for the panel structure of the data by including time dummy variables as well as estimating robust standard errors that are clustered in the firm. Additional analysis is reported in the online appendix, Table A.6. 6About 4.5% of our cases are missing demographic data at the zip-code level from the U.S. Census (likely due to shifting zip codes). The missing zip codes have slightly lower HPV rates and likely possess higher than average incomes. Given this pattern, we likely underestimate demographic effects on compliance bias. 7 A detailed description of this measure and a robustness check, using five-digit zip codes (the results were substantively similar) is presented in the online appendix (Section 3, Table A.3). 512 david m. konisky and christopher reenock eventually being signed off by the agency head. Com- pare this to a state such as South Carolina, where these actions are signed off by civil servants located five levels below the agency head. The resulting variable ranges between (0) and (1), where zero represents perfectly centralized decision-making authority, and one repre- sents authority decentralized to the field-officer level. This equation yields a measure of locational authority and is available for three levels of enforcement action across each state—Level I actions (informal and formal notices that typically are reserved for the first step in a case of noncompliance), Level II actions (formal administrative actions, which may include penalties), and Level III actions (civil and criminal cases filed against a noncompliant entity). We standardized each of these measures and added them to construct an equally weighted scale of sign-off authority. The final measure, Signature Authority, has a mean of approx- imately zero and a standard deviation of 2.5. Control Variables Firms and regulatory officers rely on a host of signals to inform their decisions. Given that these signals may be correlated with their compliance decisions as well as with the demographic composition of the relevant community, we include several controls to avoid drawing incorrect inferences. To account for relevant policy task factors, we include measures of problem severity and complexity in the local policy arena. We measure problem severity with Nonattain- ment, a count of the number of CAA ambient air- quality standards a county fails to meet on an annual basis. We also include Policy Entropy, a diversity index of state air-emissions sources in a county, where higher values represent a more complex implementa- tion environment (Potoski 1999). Last, many states have decentralized their CAA compliance-monitoring activities to regional offices. To control for each office’s workload, we include Regional Scale, which is the total number of regulated firms in the region. Firms’ and bureaucrats’ compliance decisions may also be influenced by economic and political condi- tions. To account for economic conditions, we use Unemployment Rate, measured at the county-level. In addition, we include a measure of industry salience as the percentage of a given county’s total nonfarm income that derives from Air Polluting Industries (Ringquist 1993). Political factors at both the state and local level may also affect compliance decisions. A stronger Democratic presence in state government has been associated with greater regulatory activity in general (Scholz, Twombly, and Headrick 1991; Scholz and Wei 1986), and in enforcement of the CAA in particular (Konisky 2007; Wood 1992). To account for state-level political influence, we include Democratic Governor, a dummy variable reflecting gubernatorial partisan control, and Percentage Democrats in State Legislature, which is the total percentage of Democrats in both state houses. Past research has also shown that regulators are responsive to local political conditions (Scholz, Twombly, and Headrick 1991; Scholz and Wei 1986; but see Huber 2007). Given that minorities tend to live in more Democratic areas, and state governments led by Democrats tend to pursue more enforcement, it is important to control for any local political effects, which we do with Percent Democratic Vote, which is the county-level percentage of the 2000 presidential vote for the Democratic candidate. Last, we include a set of firm-level controls to account for heterogeneity in compliance costs across firm types and for variation in the political costs that officers face in handling cases for different types of firms. First, firms with a recent agency-inspection history are more likely to assign a higher cost to future noncompliance. Therefore, we include two dichoto- mous inspection variables in the firm model that indicate whether it has been inspected in the prior year, State Inspection and Federal Inspection. Moreover, regulatory officers will be more likely to incur greater political costs for failing to detect a prior noncompliant firm. Therefore, in the regulatory detection model, we include two dichotomous enforcement actions variables that indicate whether the firm has been punished with at least one enforcement action in the prior year, State Enforcement Action and Federal Enforcement Action. We also include three firm-level dummy variables reflecting a facility’s industrial classification code: Manufacturing, Utilities, and Transportation. Last, we also included a firm-level variable reflecting the level of pollution generated by the regulated entity. This variable, Major Source, is a dummy variable that is coded one if the firm is classified as a major source of air pollution (generally greater than 100 tons per year) and zero if it is not. Empirical Results Before describing the results from estimating the DCE model, it is important to recall that the model consists of two sets of estimated parameters. For the first set, the firm model, positive coefficients reflect an increase in the probability of a firm being an HPV. For the second set, the detection model, positive coeffi- cients reflect an increase in the probability of a firm compliance bias and environmental (in)justice 513 being detected as an HPV. In addition, it is important to note that the mean of the group-mobilization and signature authority variables are essentially zero. Ac- cordingly, the parameters on the constituent terms, Percentage of African American Population and Percent- age of Hispanic Population, represent the effect of either community demographic when both mobilization and signature authority are at their respective means. The results are displayed in Table 1. Given space constraints, we focus our discussion on the variables of central theoretical interest. Across both the firm and detection models, the results are generally con- sistent with our expectations. The estimates from the firm model suggest that community demographics have statistically significant associations with a firm’s HPV classification. Specifically, firms located in His- panic communities and lower socioeconomic status communities are more likely to be noncompliant with the CAA. Firms located in African American commun- ities, however, are not more likely to be major violators—a finding that cuts against our expectations and claims made by many environmental justice advocates. It is also worth noting that the coefficients on the Hispanic and class variables are of greater magnitude than those derived from a single-equation probit model, which highlights the problem of model- ing compliance without taking into account the com- pliance bias inherent in the data.8 (We present estimates from a probit model in Section 2 of the online appendix.) The estimates in the detection model suggest that community demographics are also systematically as- sociated with the likelihood of regulatory officers accurately detecting noncompliant firms. The percent- age of Hispanics (but not African Americans) in a community and a community’s socioeconomic class each have a statistically significant effect on regulatory officers’ reliably detecting noncompliance. The results suggest that, on average, regulators are less likely to detect HPVs in these communities. Taking the results of both models together, we now have a clearer picture of the process behind disparities in environmental regulatory outputs. Relative to those located in more upper-class, non-Hispanic communities, firms are both more likely to be significant violators of the CAA and less likely to be characterized as such as by bureaucrats. This supports our expectations in both Hypothesis 1 and Hypothesis 2. What of the ability to mitigate this pattern of bias via political mobilization? Recall that our expectation is that, in more mobilized communities, firms will face greater costs associated with noncompliance, and bureaucrats will face greater costs associated with failing to detect noncompliance. To the extent that discriminatory patterns exist across community dem- ographics, these patterns ought to be attenuated in the presence of actual political mobilization. The analysis is consistent with our expectations in Hypothesis 3. The interaction terms in both the firm and detection models suggest a diminishment of bias—that is, in the presence of mobilized, Hispanic communities, firms are less likely to be noncompliant, and bureaucrats are more likely to detect noncompliance.9 (We would have expected an analogous effect in African American communities, but as noted above, the coefficient on the initial percentage African American variable does not suggest any baseline bias to attenuate.) This finding lends additional support to a widely held belief among scholars that political mobilization can effec- tively counter environmental inequities. The novelty of our findings, however, lies in demonstrating that political mobilization can alter not only firms’ com- pliance decisions, but also regulatory officers’ detection decisions.10 It also appears that the ability of political mobi- lization to mitigate this bias does not extend to other standard indicators of mobilization. We gathered data on both voter turnout from the 2000 Presiden- tial election at the county level and the number of campaign donations made to candidates annually (2001–2004) at the zip-code level. When we estimate the effect of these indicators of political mobilization, neither successfully attenuates the compliance bias present in Hispanic neighborhoods—the coefficient on the interaction term is null in both cases. We suspect that voting and campaign donations repre- sent diffuse mobilization across policy issues—too diffuse to alter the incentives of firms or regulatory officers in Hispanic communities. (These results are pro- vided in Section 4, Table A.5 in the online appendix.) Finally, the parameter estimate on the Signature Authority interaction term is consistent with our last hypothesis that institutional structures alter regula- tory officers’ incentives to detect noncompliance. 8Moreover, with a single equation, the analyst must decide whether to interpret an effect as influencing compliance or detection. 9Our mobilization measure primarily reflects groups representing persons of color and may be a less valid measure of mobilization around class issues. Including a multiplicative interaction term between mobilization and class yields a null coefficient. 10 Our results are also robust to alternative specifications of group mobilization. Specifically, we used a simple count of environ- mental justice groups, and differentiated between groups focused on African American and Hispanic issues when creating our interaction terms. These results are reported in the online appendix (Section 3, Table A.4). 514 david m. konisky and christopher reenock TA B L E 1 High Priority Violator Status for Individual Regulated Firms HPV Status Bivariate Probit, with Partial Observability Firm Model Pr(Observing HPV) Detection Model Pr(Detection) b s.e. b b s.e. b Environmental Justice Indicators % African American 0.0002 0.0010 0.0003 0.0013 % Hispanic 0.0069*** 0.0011 -0.0069*** 0.0014 Class -0.0632** 0.0254 0.0635** 0.0320 Mobilization 0.1011** 0.0402 -0.0962* 0.0494 Mobilization X African American -0.0011 0.0008 0.0008 0.0009 Mobilization X Hispanic -0.0024*** 0.0007 0.0022** 0.0009 Signature Authority — — -0.0216*** 0.0054 Sig. Authority X African American — — 0.0000 0.0002 Sig. Authority X Hispanic — — 0.0008*** 0.0002 Policy Task Factor Indicators Regional Scale 0.0003*** 0.0001 -0.0001 0.0001 Policy Entropy -0.0474 0.0282 0.0860** 0.0351 Nonattainment 0.0994*** 0.0431 -0.0634 0.0535 Economic Context Indicators Unemployment 0.0850 0.0117 -0.0761*** 0.0143 % Income Air Pollution Industry 0.0076 0.0041 -0.0060 0.0049 Political Context Indicators Democratic Governor -0.1617*** 0.0302 0.1584*** 0.0396 % Democratic in State Legislature -0.0012 0.0013 0.0006 0.0017 % Democratic Vote -0.0095*** 0.0015 0.0080*** 0.0018 Firm-Level Factors State Inspection (1 Year Lag) 0.1759*** 0.0258 — — Feb Inspection (1 Year Lag) -0.0341 0.0219 — — State Enforcement Action (1 Year Lag) — — 5.4527*** 0.5632 Feb Enforcement Action (1 Year Lag) — — 1.2510*** 0.2173 Manufacturing Firm 0.0148 0.0402 0.0913* 0.0551 Utility Firm 0.0073 0.0476 -0.0621 0.0570 Transportation Firm 0.0234 0.1167 -0.0583 0.1368 Major Source 0.6429*** 0.0344 -0.2262** 0.0984 Year Dummy (2002) -0.1832*** 0.0373 0.2145*** 0.0503 Year Dummy (2003) -0.1932*** 0.0392 0.1815*** 0.0503 Year Dummy (2004) -0.2502*** 0.0388 0.2185*** 0.0499 Intercept -1.1353*** 0.1032 0.5389* 0.2785 rho -0.867** Log-Likelihood -27858.16 x2 (49) 1241.56*** Number of Cases 153580 Note: *p , .10, **p , .05, ***p , .01, two-tailed test. Standard errors clustered on firm. compliance bias and environmental (in)justice 515 The results suggest a statistically significant interaction between percentage of Hispanic residents in a com- munity and the location of enforcement authority. When this authority rests with field officers, while a certain degree of failed detection still exists, field officers are less sensitive to whether a community is Hispanic. In other words, the detection of noncompliance is relatively flat across levels of Hispanic communities. However, when enforcement authority is centralized near the top of the agency’s chain of command, a different type of pressure arises. For these high-level managers, the detection of noncompliance wanes in the presence of an increasingly more Hispanic community. This relationship is consistent with our argument that bureaucrats near the top of the agency’s structure feel greater pressure for their agency to perform well (i.e., produce high compliance) and as such are more sensitive to registering noncompliance in heavily Hispanic communities. It is worth noting that this relationship is not conditional on party control of the governor’s office. In models not reported, we included a three-way interaction term—Democratic Governor X Signature Authority X % Hispanic (and similarly for % African-American)—but the coefficient was not statistically significant, suggesting that high-level bu- reaucrats’ compliance determinations are not condi- tioned by executive political control. This is consistent with the idea that high-level managers, across political contexts, worry about maintaining a positive image of their agency. Figure 1 better demonstrates the substantive effects of these findings. Each of the panels display the marginal effect of a 10% increase in the percent- age of the population that is Hispanic in a zip code on the joint probability of observing a noncompliant, undetected firm.11 The top panel displays the mar- ginal effect of Hispanic across the mobilization scale, while the lower panel displays the effect across the signature authority scale.12 The top panel of Figure 1 shows that regulatory officers respond to Hispanic communities differently, conditioned on whether those communities are more mobilized around environmental justice concerns. In fact, the number of undetected noncompliant firms (nationwide) can decrease from a high of approx- imately 150 in the absence of mobilized communities to nearly 50 in the presence of highly mobilized ones. A decrease of 100 HPVs nationally may appear to some to be a diminutive effect, but the presence of a single HPV can be quite impactful for the surround- ing community. Direct mobilization of at-risk com- munities is not the only incentive mechanism that affects regulator decision making. The lower panel suggests that the location of signature authority within an agency is a powerful incentive device as well. While all agency bureaucrats engage in some amount of failed detection (i.e., the expected number FI GU R E 1 Effect of Percent Hispanic on Undetected HPVs across Mobilization and Signature Authority 11 The substantive effect that we report is the change in the unconditional joint probability of observing a noncompliant firm, that is likely to have gone undetected, or Pr y1 ¼ 1;ð y2 ¼ 0Þ¼ F x1b1ð Þ� F2 x1b1; x2b2; rð Þ multiplies by the total number of firms for whom the condition is reasonable (see next note for explanation). 12The figures were created by estimating the mean expected probability and associated standard errors from 10,000 draws off of the variance-covariance matrix. To display a substantively interesting outcome, we multiplied the marginal probability for a given condition by the nationwide subset of the firm population for whom an additional 10% Hispanic gain is reasonable (approximately 18%, or 6,913 firms for our data). This calcu- lation produced the expected change in the number of unde- tected noncompliant firms across the United States. 516 david m. konisky and christopher reenock of undetected noncompliant firms is positive over the entire range of signature authority), those officers nearer the top of an agency’s chain of command succumb to an additional disincentive to code non- compliance. At the extreme, in the presence of a more Hispanic community, when decision making over enforcement rests with high-level bureaucrats, nearly 140 noncompliant HPVs will go undetected compared to 80 when such authority rests with field officers. We believe that this is due to high-level bureaucrats being more likely to engage in organizational cheating in the presence of a community that is less politically mobi- lized and therefore less likely or able to engage in fire- alarm oversight.13 The relative impact of the mobilization and signature authority variables on the joint probability of observing an undetected violating firm compares reasonably well with other variables in the model. For example, having a Democratic governor decreases the number of undetected violators by an estimated 290 firms, nationally. This suggests that the greatest impact of mobilization or signature authority (;150) is nearly half the magnitude of changing the party of the governor’s office. Another factor, local-level partisan representation, also motivates firms and regulators. An increase of a standard deviation (about14 points) above the average percent of the Democratic county vote in the 2000 presidential election (around 46%), decreases the number of undetected violators by an estimated 200 firms, nationally. These results are consistent with long-held findings in the literature that central and local partisan actors shape policy delivery (Scholz and Wei 1986). But, our analysis reveals two alternate and meaningful pathways to influence com- munity compliance bias—one emphasizing commun- ity empowerment and political mobilization and the other emphasizing regulatory officers’ incentives struc- tures via creative-agency design features. Discussion and Conclusion Democratic governments continue to wrestle with shortfalls in equitable policy delivery. Examining the occurrence of such shortfalls has been a central focus of scholars and practitioners alike. In this article, we focused on one area, environmental policy, for which research has failed to arrive at a consensus on the causal process that generates bias in regulatory out- comes. We have attempted to move this discussion in a different direction—one that considers the incen- tives of both firms and regulatory officers making decisions about compliance. Our argument suggests that disparities in U.S. environmental policy outcomes are rooted in the incentives facing both firms and the bureaucrats tasked with implementation. Although past research has recognized the dual production of compliance bias, we offered a novel theoretical account focusing on the incentives of bureaucrats to code firm com- pliance status. This approach enabled us to then show how decisions change in the presence of variation in these incentives. We demonstrated that when com- munities overcome collective action problems, bu- reaucrats will dedicate more resources to the firms in their areas. We also showed that agency design can accentuate bias in compliance decisions. High-ranking bureaucrats have an incentive to overreport compli- ance rates, since these rates are used as indicators of agency performance by external stakeholders. Because these bureaucrats are less likely to get caught engaging in this behavior when communities have fewer polit- ical resources to detect it, the outcome is likely to further disadvantage poor and minority communities since they tend to lack these resources. An unanticipated finding is that the bias revealed from our analysis pertains to poor and Hispanic communities, but not African American ones. It is worth noting that this result would have been masked had we just considered minorities collectively, which is often done in the literature. What might explain this pattern, and particularly the lack of bias in firm and regulatory compliance decisions toward firms located in African American communities? The simplest interpretation, of course, is that there is no systematic bias. Although this runs counter to claims made in the literature (e.g., Bryant 1995; Bullard 1993), it would be welcome news for these communities which past work has found to be subject to disproportionate environ- mental burdens (Ringquist 2005). It may also reflect the time period analyzed. Our analysis was limited to 2001–2004, and by this time, the environmental justice movement was quite mature in many African American communities, and firms and regulators alike may have factored in the costs of committing major violations and failing to detect noncompliance, re- spectively. In other words, advocacy in these com- munities may have paid considerable dividends by the time of our study. For Hispanics, however, the results 13We also considered the possibility that mobilized groups might change the decision calculus for upper-level bureaucrats. We examined whether a three-way interaction was present between Hispanic community, mobilization, and signature authority, but the coefficient was not statistically significant. compliance bias and environmental (in)justice 517 suggest a more traditional story of environmental disparities. Firms in these communities are not only more likely to be significant violators of their CAA obligations, but they are less likely to be designated as such by regulatory officers. There are several additional implications of our study. While our findings suggest that substantial disparities in compliance outcomes exist, they also suggest the possibility that patterns of bias stem from the decision-making structures of regulatory officers, not necessarily from intentional discrimination. This by no means discounts the importance of the disparate outcomes, but it does suggest that the source of bias need not rest with deliberate prejudice, but with bureaucrats’ rational responses to their resource con- straints. In other words, biased outcomes are possible, indeed probable, even in the absence of explicit discrimination. Our results also offer a cautionary note on goal displacement. Political principals can use various performance measures to determine agency ‘‘suc- cess.’’ However, in certain contexts, indicators such as compliance rates may present perverse incentives to regulatory officers. Our analysis suggests that when bureaucrats face such perverse incentives, they may substitute the appearance of successful policy delivery for equitable policy delivery. Assessing the way in which such indicators incentivize regulatory officers is essential for any effort to reducing compliance bias. Given the increasing prevalence of performance measurement at all levels of government, the poten- tial implications of this type of goal displacement on equitable policy implementation likely extends into many different areas of public policy. Last, our study reveals evidence of multiple ways that class- and race-based disparities could be re- dressed. Communities could be empowered through capacity-building efforts. Such efforts designed to help poor and minority areas organize around issues of environmental protection will produce a demand for more equitable treatment from government and put direct pressure on firms to improve their perform- ance. Second, our results suggest that changes to the institutional decision-making structure of the agencies responsible for implementing policy would also be effective. Specifically, our analysis suggests that decen- tralizing authority to regulatory officers in agencies could result in fewer cases of deliberate nondetection of compliance. That is, moving the location of compliance determinations away from high-ranking officials with incentives to overreport compliance may result in fairer—although not necessarily fair— treatment of communities hosting regulated firms. Acknowledgments We would like to thank Don Haider-Markel, Eliz- abeth Rigby, and Evan Ringquist for helpful com- ments and discussion, as well as John Mortara and Kristen Holder for their excellent research assistance. References Abowd, John M., and Henry S. Farber. 1982. ‘‘Job Queues and The Union Status of Workers.’’ Industrial and Labor Relations Review 35 (3): 354–67. Blau, Peter M., and Marshall W. Meyer. 1971. Bureaucracy in Modern Society. 2nd ed. New York: Random House. Bohte, John, and Kenneth J. Meier. 2000. ‘‘Goal Displacement: Assessing the Motivation for Organizational Cheating.’’ Public Administration Review 60 (2): 173–82. Braithwaite, John, and Toni Makkai. 1991. ‘‘Testing an Expected Utility Model of Corporate Deterrence.’’ Law & Society Review 25 (1): 7–40. Brehm, John, and Scott Gates. 1997. Working, Shirking, and Sabotage: Bureaucratic Response to a Democratic Public. Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press. Brehm, John, and James T. Hamilton. 1996. ‘‘Noncompliance in Environmental Reporting: Are Violators Ignorant, or Evasive, of the Law?’’ American Journal of Political Science 40 (2): 444–77. Bryant, Bunyan. 1995. Environmental Justice: Issues, Policies, and Solutions. Washington, DC: Island Press. Bullard, Robert D. 1993. ‘‘Anatomy of Environmental Racism and the Environmental Justice Movement.’’ In Confronting Environmental Racism: Voices from the Grassroots, ed. R. D. Bullard. Boston: South End Press, 15–39. Bullard, Robert D. and Glenn S. Johnson. 2000. ‘‘Environmental Justice: Grassroots Activism and Its Impact on Public Policy Decision Making.’’ Journal of Social Issues 56 (3): 555–78. Dion, Catherine, Paul Lanoie, and Benoit Laplante. 1998. ‘‘Monitoring of Pollution Regulation: Do Local Conditions Matter?’’ Journal of Regulatory Economics 13 (1): 5–18. Downs, Anthony. 1967. Inside Bureaucracy. Boston: Little, Brown. Earnhart, Dietrich. 2004a. ‘‘Regulatory Factors Shaping Environ- mental Performance at Publicly-Owned Treatment Plants.’’ Journal of Environmental Economics and Management 48 (1): 655–81. Earnhart, Dietrich. 2004b. ‘‘The Effects of Community Charac- teristics on Polluter Compliance Levels.’’ Land Economics 80 (3): 408–32. Environmental Justice Resource Center. 2000. People of Color Environmental Groups Directory. Atlanta: Environmental Jus- tice Resource Center. Feinstein, Jonathan S. 1990. ‘‘Detection Controlled Estimation.’’ Journal of Law & Economics 53 (1): 233–76. Feinstein, Jonathan S. 1999. ‘‘Approaches to Estimating Non- compliance: Examples from Federal Taxation in the United States.’’ The Economic Journal 109 (456): 360–69. Gray, Wayne B., and Ronald J. Shadbegian. 2004. ‘‘‘Optimal’ Pollution Abatement: Whose Benefits Matter, and How Much?’’ Journal of Environmental Economics and Management 47 (3): 510–34. 518 david m. konisky and christopher reenock Hamilton, James T. 1993. Politics and Social Costs: Estimating the Impact of Collective Action on Hazardous Waste Facility. The RAND Journal of Economics 24 (1): 101–25. Hamilton, James T. 1995. Testing for Environmental Racism: Prejudice, Profits, Political Power? Journal of Policy Analysis and Management 14 (1): 107–32. Hamilton, James T., and W. Kip Viscusi. 1999. Calculating Risks? The Spatial and Political Dimensions of Hazardous Waste Policy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Hammond, Thomas H. 1986. ‘‘Agenda Control Organizational structure and Bureaucratic Politics.’’ American Journal of Political Science 30 (2): 379–420. Helland, Eric, 1998a, ‘‘Environmental Protection in the Federalist System: The Political Economy of NPDES Inspections.’’ Economic Inquiry 36 (2): 305–19. Helland, Eric, 1998b, ‘‘The Enforcement of Pollution Control Laws: Inspections, Violations, and Self-Reporting.’’ The Re- view of Economics and Statistics 80 (1): 141–53. Huber, Gregory A. 2007. The Craft of Bureaucratic Neutrality: Interests and Influence in Governmental Regulation of Occupa- tional Safety. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Konisky, David M. 2009. ‘‘Inequities in Enforcement? Environ- mental Justice and Government Performance.’’ Journal of Policy Analysis and Management 28 (1): 102–21. Konisky, David M., and Tyler S. Schario. 2010. ‘‘Examining Environmental Justice in Facility-Level Regulatory Enforce- ment.’’ Social Science Quarterly 91 (3): 835–55. Maravall, José Marı́a, and Adam Przeworski. 2003. Democracy and the Rule of Law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Meier, Kenneth J. 1993. ‘‘Representative Bureaucracy: A Theo- retical and Empirical Exposition.’’ In James Perry, ed., Research in Public Administration. Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. Mennis, Jeremy L. 2005. ‘‘The Distribution and Enforcement of Air Polluting Facilities in New Jersey.’’ The Professional Geographer 57 (3): 411–22. Olson, Mary K. 1995. ‘‘Regulatory Agency Discretion among Competing Industries: Inside the FDA.’’ Journal of Law, Economics, & Organization 11 (2): 379–407. Poirier, Dale J. 1980. ‘‘Partial Observability in Bivariate Probit Models. Journal of Econometrics 12: 209–17. Potoski, Matthew. 1999. ‘‘Managing Uncertainty through Bu- reaucratic Design: Administrative Procedures and State Air Pollution Control Agencies.’’ Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory 9 (4): 623–40. Raz, Joseph. 1977. ‘‘The Rule of Law and Its Virtue.’’ The Law Quarterly Review 93: 195–211. Reenock, Christopher M., and Brian J. Gerber. 2008. ‘‘Political Insulation, Information Exchange, and Interest Group Access to the Bureaucracy.’’ Journal of Public Administration Research and Theory 18 (3): 415–40. Ringquist, Evan J. 1993. Environmental Protection at the State Level. Armonk, NY: M.E. Sharpe. Ringquist, Evan J. 2005. ‘‘Assessing Evidence of Environmental Inequities: A Meta-Analysis.’’ Journal of Policy Analysis and Management 24 (2): 223–47. Scholz, John T. 1991. ‘‘Cooperative Regulatory Enforcement and the Politics of Administrative Effectiveness.’’ American Polit- ical Science Review 85 (1): 115–36. Scholz, John T., Jim Twombly, and Barbara Headrick. 1991. ‘‘Street-Level Political Controls over Federal Bu- reaucracy.’’ American Political Science Review 85 (3): 829– 50. Scholz, John T., and Wang Cheng-Lung. 2006. ‘‘Cooptation or Transformation? Local Policy Networks and Federal Regula- tory Enforcement.’’ American Journal of Political Science 50 (1): 81–97. Scholz, John T., and Wei Feng-Heng. 1986. ‘‘Regulatory Enforce- ment in a Federalist System.’’ American Political Science Review 80 (4): 1249–70. Simon, Herbert. 1976. Administrative Behavior, 3rd Edition. New York: The Free Press. Wilson, James Q. 1989. Bureaucracy: What Government Agencies Do and Why They Do It. New York: Basic Books. Winter, Soren, and Peter May. 2001. ‘‘Motivation for Compli- ance with Environmental Regulation.’’ Journal of Policy Analysis and Management 20 (4): 675–98. Wood, B. Dan. 1992. ‘‘Modeling Federal Implementation as a System: The Clean Air Case.’’ American Journal of Political Science 36 (1): 40–67. David M. Konisky is Assistant Professor at Georgetown University, Washington, DC 20057. Christopher Reenock is Associate Professor at Florida State University, Tallahassee, FL 32306. compliance bias and environmental (in)justice 519 work_2i4onyceabcetmg2mkrrcuncre ---- Blockchain technology – the ultimate solution for utmost cybersecurity LOGIN YourStory YourStory Club YourStoryTV HerStory SocialStory SMBStory More Companies Advertise With Us Makers-India AutoStory MyStory Weekender Journal YS Korea Deutschland Germany Events Visual English Kannada Hindi Tamil Asamiya Bangla Gujarati Malayalam Marathi Odia Punjabi Telugu Urdu அ अ ಅ Login English Kannada Hindi Tamil Asamiya Bangla Gujarati Malayalam Marathi Odia Punjabi Telugu Urdu அ अ ಅ Login Disclaimer: This is a user generated content for MyStory, a YourStory initiative to enable its community to contribute and have their voices heard. The views and writings here reflect that of the author and not of YourStory. Blockchain technology – the ultimate solution for utmost cybersecurity By Arpita Arya|2nd Feb 2018 Blockchain technology has created a sensation in the internet space. Let's get to learn more about the concept and terminologies.  0 claps +0 Share on 0 claps +0 Share on Share on What Is Blockchain Technology? Blockchain technology came into existence in 2008 and with the introduction of bitcoins, it became popular worldwide. According to Wikipedia, “blockchain is a continuously growing list of records, called blocks, which are linked and secured using cryptography”. This technology has created a sensation in the internet space which was originally invented by Satoshi Nakamoto.  Trading in cryptocurrencies does involve the high degree of risk. To solve these major concerns many tech communities like Blockchain-hero.com is spending sleepless nights to find other potential uses and solutions for the blockchain technology. The best part of this technology is that it eliminates the need for a third party to control the database which is shared among all the users. This distributed yet secured system initiated a new trend among the internet with lots of future scopes. Evolution Of Transaction Data Storage Data storage changed drastically after the invention of digital currencies also known as a cryptocurrency. In today’s date, there are more than 700 Bitcoin-like cryptocurrencies available in the market. They have finally set up the motion to be the principal form of transaction. This is mainly due to the growing online market in the current society. People shop online and carry out numerous operations on a daily basis. The emergence of cryptocurrency aimed at minimizing the exploitation of online customers from being overcharged by the middlemen.  The system, however, requires a series of record management technique that is decentralized. These are digital ledgers that are protected with cryptology encryption. The chain contains a series of blocks that secures and stores data relating to the transaction of each. The information is then stored permanently after being recorded and for later use and cannot be altered by a third party. The system is robust, transparent and incorruptible. Hence, the technology behind this system has gained so much attention worldwide. Why Implement Restricted Measures In Transactional Data Storage No person should be trusted with another person’s transactional data. Human beings will always act in self-interest. This has become the main motivating factor for blockchain sites advocating for implementation of blockchain system. The private key cryptography is the reason why bitcoin and cryptocurrencies were successful. Each user of the blockchain system has a secure transactional key that allows them to access their transactional data. Any other person can not manipulate the key. The key is also assigned to the user with a personal login signature. The signature is approved by all peers in the network for a transaction to take place. This system of encryption ensures data does not fall into fraudulent hands providing ultimate security. Trends In Blockchain technology Banks and Financial Institutions are trying to implement blockchain data storage technology into their systems to secure transactional data and track their financial activities at an optimum level. Financial institutions are already applying the system boost of unhackable systems. Various industries are also trying to create a reliable environment for their operations through creating unaltered systems that cannot be hacked or manipulated. Thus creating a perfect environment for forecasting and planning of their activities in the most secure manner. Get Inspired Innovation Business 0 Shares +0 Share on 0 Shares +0 Share on Share on Trending Now Trending Stories How Managed IT Services Benefit the Manufacturing Industry Arts and Social perception Google Doodle today celebrates the start of spring Ecommerce Mistakes That Make Your Users Abandon Your Website Daily Capsule Meesho turns unicorn, Swiggy raises mega round Read the full story Latest Updates from around the world Arts and Social perception How To Monitor Employees' Productivity? Art and environment Google Doodle today celebrates the start of spring A New CMO Role: Leveraging an Organization’s Purpose for Strategic Advantage How to accelerate Digital Business in 2021 Didn't find what you were looking for? Search for what you want, categories, tags, keywords, authors, events, anything under YourStory SEARCH Topics Tech Reviews Growth Hacks Government And Legal About Advertise with us About Meet the team Report an issue Contact Us Work with us Events © 2021 YourStory Media Pvt. Ltd. Privacy Policy v2.3.036 Built with ♥ in India work_2livftbyzjb6lpqq5643orum6e ---- Edinburgh Research Explorer Restorative justice informed criminal justice social work and probation services Citation for published version: Kirkwood, S & Hamad, R 2019, 'Restorative justice informed criminal justice social work and probation services', Probation Journal, vol. 66, no. 4, pp. 398-415. https://doi.org/10.1177/0264550519880595 Digital Object Identifier (DOI): 10.1177/0264550519880595 Link: Link to publication record in Edinburgh Research Explorer Document Version: Peer reviewed version Published In: Probation Journal Publisher Rights Statement: The final version of this paper has been published in Probation Journal, Vol/Issue, Month/Year by SAGE Publications Ltd, All rights reserved. © Steve Kirkwood, Rania Hamad, 2019. It is available at: https://doi.org/10.1177/0264550519880595 General rights Copyright for the publications made accessible via the Edinburgh Research Explorer is retained by the author(s) and / or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing these publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Take down policy The University of Edinburgh has made every reasonable effort to ensure that Edinburgh Research Explorer content complies with UK legislation. If you believe that the public display of this file breaches copyright please contact openaccess@ed.ac.uk providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 06. Apr. 2021 https://doi.org/10.1177/0264550519880595 https://doi.org/10.1177/0264550519880595 https://www.research.ed.ac.uk/portal/en/publications/restorative-justice-informed-criminal-justice-social-work-and-probation-services(b29a33da-c577-4c85-a365-900ebac7579e).html 1 Restorative justice informed criminal justice social work Steve Kirkwood & Rania Hamad The University of Edinburgh Citation Kirkwood, S. & Hamad, R. (In press). Restorative justice informed criminal justice social work. Probation Journal. Abstract Despite the growth of restorative justice research, theory and practice, little work has explored its implications for criminal justice social work and probation services. Our analysis demonstrates a restorative justice ‘lens’ transforms the view of criminal justice social work, enlarging the scope to help people make amends for harm, magnifying the role for victims of crime, refocusing on the meaningfulness of reparative acts, and clarifying the role of communities in reintegration. Our vision of restorative justice informed criminal justice social work offers a way of shifting practice to help people repair harm, make good and move on with their lives. Corresponding author Dr Steve Kirkwood The University of Edinburgh Chrystal Macmillan Building 15a George Square Edinburgh EH8 9LD United Kingdom Email: s.kirkwood@ed.ac.uk Funding This research received no specific grant from any funding agency in the public, commercial, or not- for-profit sectors. Declaration of conflicting interests The Authors declare that there is no conflict of interest. Acknowledgements We would like to thank John Devaney, Jenny Johnstone and the reviewers for their helpful comments on early drafts of this article. mailto:s.kirkwood@ed.ac.uk 2 A new lens Howard Zehr (1991) described restorative justice (RJ) as a lens. Looking through this lens, you see crime as a form of harm to people and relationships. You also see the needs and obligations that harm creates, such as the need to get answers and the obligation to take responsibility for your actions. From this perspective, the best way of repairing harm is for people to talk to each other about what happened, about the effects it had, and about what could be done to set things right. For the person who caused the harm, this allows them to apologise for their behaviour, make amends, and commit themselves to going straight. For the person who was harmed, they can tell their story of how they were hurt, learn why it happened, be recognised for their inherent worth, and say what they think the other person should do to make good. Everyone has an opportunity to be heard, learn, and rebuild trust. In most jurisdictions, this is not the standard response to crime. In Scotland in 2016/17, almost half of the people convicted in court received a financial penalty; 14% were imprisoned and 20% received a community sentence (Scottish Government, 2018a). Even though Scotland (along with England and Wales) has the highest imprisonment rate in Western Europe (World Prison Brief, 2018), more people are supervised in the community than locked up in prison. In the age of ‘mass probation’ (Phelps, 2016), the number of people on community sentences greatly outnumbers those sentenced to prison in many jurisdictions around the world (McNeill and Beyens, 2014). It is therefore surprising that, despite the mounting evidence for the effectiveness of RJ (e.g., Strang et al., 2013), few people have considered what the RJ perspective reveals about the nature and possibilities for criminal justice social work (CJSW)1. We invite you to view CJSW through the RJ lens and examine how it unveils, magnifies or distorts aspects of existing practice. The RJ perspective sees crime in a different light. From this viewpoint, the nature of crime is different, with corresponding principles, processes and intended outcomes for responding to crime. Rather than treating crime as a breach of rules against the state, crime is seen as a form of harm inflicted on one person by another, damaging relationships between them and communities (Zehr, 1991). For RJ, responses to crime ought to focus on mending these relationships. Participation should be voluntary, as this empowers people to take responsibility for their actions and make choices about their future. The process should focus on dialogue, efforts to come to a mutual agreement, and include symbolic and practical steps to address the harm. The intended outcomes are to bring back moral responsibility to the person who committed the harm, restore a sense of control and dignity to the person who was harmed, and reassert trusting relationships with the community (Morris, 2002). However, definitions of RJ are contested (Wood and Suzuki, 2016). ‘Purist’ definitions of RJ describe it primarily as a process, focusing on dialogue between those affected by crime (e.g., McCold, 2000) whereas ‘maximalist’ definitions are broader, encompassing a range of processes aimed at achieving restorative outcomes (Walgrave, 2000). Here, we take Zehr's (1991) view of RJ as a perspective on crime and justice, in order to re-vision CJSW, while paying special attention to RJ as a ‘justice mechanism’ involving dialogue between those responsible for and harmed by crime (Daly, 2016). Our argument is that viewing CJSW from the perspective of RJ supports the development of RJ practices and processes (especially dialogue among those affected by crime) and the realignment of CJSW as a system to better achieve restorative outcomes. 1 Throughout this article, ‘criminal justice social work’ (CJSW) refers to those services responsible for supervising people on community sentences or on licence following imprisonment (sometimes referred to as ‘probation services’ or ‘community corrections’). 3 Ward and Moreton (2008) suggest that the concept of ‘moral repair’ helps conceptualise the role of responding to offending behaviour. Walker (2006: 6) defined moral repair as ‘the process of moving from the situation of loss and damage to a situation where some degree of stability in moral relations is regained.’ She said ‘[r]estorative justice exemplifies moral repair’ (229) as it addresses needs and obligations to repair harm, rebuilds trust and instils hope for positive future relations. For Ward and Moreton, moral repair provides a normative framework for addressing both the harm caused and harm suffered by the person subject to supervision. However, moral repair is not a private matter. For the person responsible for the harm, addressing their moral obligations is a way of bringing them back in line with the smooth functioning of society (London, 2003). For the person harmed, receiving an apology and efforts to make amends allows them to have greater trust in the world they live in and confidence to live in it. As explained by Walker, when someone experiences criminal harm, it not only damages their trust in the person who committed the harm, but may reduce their trust in society more generally, such as the expectation that their home is safe from intruders or that they can walk freely without fear of attack. Therefore, there is a community dimension to the effects of criminal harm and a community interest in responding to it. McCold (2000) provided a model of RJ that includes these three constituents: people responsible for harm; people harmed by crime; and communities affected by crime. He suggested that an intervention could only be considered ‘fully restorative’ if it engages all constituents; interventions are ‘mostly restorative’ if they include two constituents and ‘partly restorative’ if they include one constituent. Interventions that do not include restorative principles are not restorative, or may be ‘pseudo restorative’ if they lay claim to restorative principles but do not enact them (e.g., lay panels that enforce compulsory punishments). We will use McCold's framework with an RJ lens to examine the way CJSW services engage with these different constituents. Criminal justice social work in Scotland We focus on Scotland, a particular case with parallels in other jurisdictions internationally. The consideration of Scotland is particularly pertinent given the recent commitment by the Scottish Government (2018b: 105) to make ‘restorative justice services widely available across Scotland by 2023’. The Scottish Government's (2019: 4) action plan on restorative justice is intended to develop RJ approaches where ‘the needs of persons harmed and their voices are central, and supports a reduction in harmful behaviour across our communities’ (Scottish Government, 2019: 4) and ‘Establish the most effective model for restorative justice in Scotland’ (Scottish Government, 2019: 10). Our article is intended as a constructive contribution to these developments and a reflection on their possible implications. Criminal justice social work (CJSW) in Scotland encompasses the services provided through local authorities by qualified social workers to people subject to the criminal justice system (Kirkwood, 2018a). The main intended outcomes of CJSW are: ‘Community safety and public protection’, ‘The reduction of re-offending’ and ‘Social inclusion to support desistance from offending’ (Scottish Government, 2010b: 15). The services supervise people on community sentences and those subject to supervision following a period of imprisonment, as well as providing diversion from prosecution services, bail supervision, voluntary throughcare services to support those leaving prison, groupwork programmes, and reports to the courts to help inform sentencing. The main community sentences in Scotland are ‘Community Payback Orders’, which have a supervision requirement and / or a requirement for the individual to undertake an amount of unpaid work, and may have other additional requirements relating to, for instance, drug treatment, alcohol treatment, mental health treatment or conduct (Scottish Government, 2010a). The services work in partnership with other statutory and voluntary agencies in the delivery of community justice services, including the risk management of people convicted of sexual offences or otherwise deemed to pose a high risk of 4 offending. Although CJSW mostly works with people on the grounds of their offending behaviour, it also has a role in relation to people with respect to their experiences as victims of crime (discussed further below). Restoring people responsible for crime One of the main aims of CJSW is to reduce the likelihood of further offending. Social workers achieve this through helping people address issues in their lives that relate to their offending behaviour. This practice is based on empirical research on ‘what works’ for addressing offending behaviour (Bonta and Andrews, 2017) and core correctional skills (Chadwick et al., 2015). Research suggests that, on average, RJ reduces offending behaviour, and therefore it may help achieve this aim (Sherman and Strang, 2007; Strang et al., 2013). The values and principles underpinning RJ are strongly aligned with those underpinning CJSW practice. The now well-established research on key factors that encourage desistance from crime have shaped CJSW in Scotland (Scottish Government, 2010a). Elements such as creating and maintaining positive relationships with service users (sometimes referred to as a ‘therapeutic relationship’ or ‘working alliance’; McNeill, Batchelor, Burnett, & Knox, 2005: 3), characterised by empathy, warmth, respect and genuineness, and utilising a person-centred, collaborative approach to supportively engender change, are all commensurate with the values and skills required for RJ. Communication, counselling, engagement, and inter-personal skills, as well as a non-judgemental approach and conveying a genuine sense of acceptance of the person, are viewed as crucial for CJSW (McNeill et al., 2005; Trotter, 2014) and these skills are clearly transferable to RJ practice. However, Ward, Fox and Garber (2015) argued that RJ theory is poorly developed regarding how it reduces offending because it does not really connect with research or theory on rehabilitation. So how might RJ reduce offending? The most influential explanation is Braithwaite's (1989) theory of reintegrative shaming. Braithwaite and Mugford (1994) proposed that RJ contributes to reducing offending through the leverage created by being exposed to victims’ accounts of the harm caused in an environment where the normal defensive mechanisms are removed, through the social pressure created by feeling shame in front of people they care about, and through a supportive response that condemns the harmful act while affirming the individual’s inherent moral worth and assisting them to make positive changes in their life. However, based on their research in England, Robinson and Shapland (2008) argued that the theory does not match the practice. They highlighted that shame tends to be experienced before rather than induced during the RJ meeting, that supporters for the person responsible for the harm are usually absent from RJ meetings, and that mechanisms supporting positive change following an RJ event were weak or inconsistent. Despite this, they still found that RJ tended to reduce the likelihood of further offending (Shapland et al., 2008). They suggest that rather than RJ reducing offending behaviour in the ways described by Braithwaite and Mugford, it is better understood as providing an opportunity to consolidate a decision to desist from further offending (Robinson and Shapland, 2008). Plans that are agreed to voluntarily and through mutual discussion are more likely to be fulfilled than those that are imposed (Latimer et al., 2005; Marshall, 1999). RJ has the potential both to reinforce commitment to the requirements of criminal justice orders (e.g., attendance of supervision meetings, completion of unpaid work hours, engagement in drug treatment programmes) if they are discussed within RJ processes, and identify additional non-compulsory goals (e.g., addressing other issues in a person’s life or seeking employment). When used in combination, the potential of both the restorative and rehabilitative work is maximised (Latimer et al., 2005). Similarly, Ward et al. (2015) suggest that, while it is unclear how RJ contributes to rehabilitation, it has a more obvious role in relation to desistance. One part of desistance involves developing an identity as a moral person (i.e., non-offender) (Maruna, 2001; Paternoster et al., 2016; Rocque et al., 5 2016). Engagement in RJ provides an opportunity for an individual to develop a desistance identity. Together with the person harmed, and other important people in their life, they can write the story of their offending behaviour so it becomes not only a narrative about someone who did wrong, but rather someone who has made steps towards redemption by seeking to understand the harm caused, offering an apology, making amends and taking steps to avoid future harmful behaviour. In so doing, they reinforce a core moral self, demonstrating they understand the wrongfulness of offending behaviour and living this out through forms of reparation. This is not a solitary act; restorative processes allow these understandings to be mutually co-created and reflected back to the person by people who matter: the victim, family, friends and (potentially) community representatives. The development of a desistance narrative may help the person to desist from offending behaviour through structuring and giving meaning to their behaviour in ways that reinforce pro-social behaviour (Maruna and Farrall, 2004). It also provides a narrative that may be acceptable to the wider community, potentially facilitating their reintegration in society. Reintegration is a further aim of CJSW; like rehabilitation (McNeill, 2009), it can be treated instrumentally, as a contributor towards reducing offending (e.g., the positive influence of having a good job and positive friendships), or as an end itself. As argued by Maruna (2006), ‘restorative re- integration’ should be community-led, reparation-based, symbolically rich and involve ‘wiping the slate clean’. RJ may help by reconciling people with their communities through making amends for the harm they have caused. This allows them to be, and to be seen to be, a person who accepts the moral wrongness of criminal harm and has taken steps towards making things right. This is most important for the direct victim of the crime, but it extends to others, such as family, friends, professionals and other members of society. As argued by Duff (2003), such reconciliation is not one- way; it may also involve the community or wider society taking some responsibility for harms the individual has suffered and taking steps to address these. RJ may be a springboard for engaging in generative activities, such paid or voluntary work, which helps them to be contributing citizens and cement a commitment to a pro-social life (Kirkwood and McNeill, 2015). Restoring people harmed by crime Peering through the RJ lens, what does CJSW engagement (and non-engagement) with victims of crime look like? In Scotland, CJSW services are intended to ‘to promote and assist the development of services to the victims of crime’ (Scottish Government, 2004). Interventions with people responsible for offending behaviour are intended to increase their understanding of the impact of crime and protect past and potential victims from harm; however, ‘Case managers would not normally contact victims direct (except for domestic abuse offences […])’ (Scottish Government, 2010a: 19). This means that work is done on behalf of actual and imagined victims, but usually without their direct involvement. Nils Christie (1977) argued professionals ‘steal’ the opportunity to deal with the crime from the person it concerns the most: the victim. The way CJSW is configured and operates, victims are largely excluded. From an RJ perspective, CJSW should support victims of crime to take part in a process of dialogue, if they so wish, so they can tell the person responsible for the crime about the effects of the harm, pose questions and receive answers about how and why the crime occurred, voice their opinion on what could be done to address the harm and reduce the likelihood of it reoccurring, and (perhaps) receive symbolic and material reparation. Restoration here does not mean returning to a state that existed before the crime. In the words of Walker (2006: 37), ‘no bell can be unrung’. However, if the victims’ needs are not addressed, further harm is done and the wounds may remain without healing (Walker, 2006). In this context, RJ is intended to restore feelings of security, self-respect, dignity and control to the victim (Morris, 2002). Pemberton, Aarten and Mulder (2018) argue that crime harms victims’ sense of agency (i.e., control over their lives) and communion (i.e., relationships with others). They suggest that RJ gives people a 6 sense of control through inviting them to co-author the narrative of the crime. When the person responsible for the offence takes responsibility and addresses fears about re-victimisation, the victim may feel more control and less fear (Pemberton, 2007; Strang et al., 2013). As argued by Walker, this has the potential to rebuild trust and instil hope, not just in terms of the relationship between the victim and the person responsible for the offence (indeed, they may have been unknown to each other before the offence and may never meet again), but in the wider sense of feeling safer in society and more optimistic about a less harmful future. If victims of crime are to engage with CJSW agencies, they will need to be reassured of the impartiality of such services (Armstrong, 2012). To what extent are CJSW practitioners able to be, and be seen to be, impartial? RJ practitioners must avoid conflicts of interest. Someone who is in a supervisory role to the individual responsible for an offence may struggle to remain impartial as a facilitator for an RJ process involving that individual. For the victim, they may also have concerns about a practitioner’s ability to be impartial if they have obligations in the role of supervisor. Ward, Gannon and Fortune (2015) suggest that an RJ perspective helps to resolve the role conflicts within the CJSW role, specifically in terms of obligations to the person responsible for the offence, the victim and wider society. They suggest that, because RJ focuses on repairing relationships, it allows practitioners to consider how they can help address the harm in relation to all constituents. Drawing on the concept of moral repair, they argue that, where obligations are in direct conflict, practitioners’ obligations are to the victim. However, this perspective also requires practitioners to address the victimisation needs of the person who was responsible for the offence (Ward and Moreton, 2008), and therefore encourages a trauma-informed response (Anderson, 2016). Practitioners must also consider the support provided to victims before, during, and following RJ processes. The consequences of victimisation and the nature of RJ processes mean that victims may require relatively intensive and ongoing support in some cases, including specialist counselling or psychological services, which may be absent or difficult to access (Thomson, 2017; Whyte and Kearney, 2017). As explained by Chapman and Chapman (2016: 142), based on experience in Northern Ireland, RJ ‘may have a therapeutic outcome but it is not therapy’. The development of RJ brings greater attention to the unmet needs of victims of crime, presenting opportunities for CJSW services to work in partnership with victim support services to seek or lobby for additional resources to support them. Although RJ is used in response to domestic abuse and sexual offences (Daly, 2006; Koss, 2014; McGlynn et al., 2012), its use in this regard remains controversial. As discussed by Roach (2000), concern for the use of RJ with victims of sexual offences and domestic abuse is understandable for several reasons: feminist organisations have fought hard to have sexual offences and domestic abuse recognised as serious crimes in many parts of the world, and they may be concerned that diverting such offences from prosecution to RJ would signal that these crimes are not serious; certain sexual offences and domestic abuse may involve forms of apology as part of the abuse cycle, therefore there is a concern that RJ may unintentionally facilitate the abusive behaviour rather than help address it; and there is a general wish to protect victims of such offences in particular from experiences that may cause further harm or disrupt processes of recovery. Many victims of sexual offences are children, which raises serious concerns about power dynamics. Indeed, Scottish Government (2017) guidance states that RJ would not normally be used in relation to sexual offences, domestic abuse, harassment or stalking, and practitioners working with such offences require specialised knowledge and skill. However, excluding domestic abuse and sexual offence from RJ may be counterproductive. If victims of such crimes wish to participate in RJ, then it would violate principles of equity to prevent them from taking part. Moreover, as women are more likely to be victims of such crimes, it would have a 7 particular effect in terms of discriminating against women participating in RJ. Given that part of recovery from crime may be regaining one’s independence, autonomy, choice, and control, denying participation may actually form part of the disempowering aspects of being a victim of crime, in the same way that standard court processes can be disempowering for such victims. Having due respect for victims of crime means properly assessing the risks; but the presence of risks should not mean the denial of access to RJ. Therefore, if RJ is going to be provided in response to crime in general, then it should also be provided in relation to sexual offences and domestic abuse. However, this is not the same as saying that diversion from prosecution is appropriate in relation to such offences; most CJSW work takes place post-conviction, and policies on diversion should be considered as a separate, although related, issue. Small-scale survey research has found support for the provision of RJ to those harmed by sexual offences, especially as an addition to (rather than instead of) going to court (Marsh and Wager, 2015). The research evidence, from the UK, Australia, New Zealand and USA, shows that RJ can be applied to sexual offences in ways that are safe, helpful and empowering (Daly, 2006; Koss, 2014; McGlynn et al., 2012). Counterintuitively, there are good arguments for CJSW services providing RJ in relation to domestic abuse. Although CJSW services in Scotland do not normally provide services directly to victims of crime, they do provide support to partners, former partners and children of men convicted of domestic abuse as part of the Caledonian System (Macrae, 2014). Practitioners have therefore developed expertise in supporting people harmed by domestic abuse. Research by Sen, Morris, Burford, Featherstone and Webb (2018) illustrates that social work services may struggle to provide appropriate interventions where families affected by domestic abuse remain together. There are many reasons why people responsible for or harmed by domestic abuse have ongoing communication and RJ is a way of responding to the needs of people in this situation; practitioners are knowledgeable on the nature of domestic abuse and capable of supporting those affected. Of all crime types, CJSW services are best placed to use RJ in relation to domestic abuse, given their arrangements and expertise for responding to such offences and supporting the victims and children. Nonetheless, when considering the use of RJ with domestic abuse, it will be vital to take the different ‘types’ of domestic abuse into account. Coercive control, whereby the perpetrator employs a range of tactics to exert power and control over partners or former partners (Johnson 2010), would require a great deal of caution in relation to utilising RJ in such circumstances, necessitating a robust assessment of suitability and joint working with children’s and partner services. To this end, the introduction of the Safe and Together™ Model of responding to domestic abuse may align with the use of RJ as part of an overall process of change. This model, premised on male perpetrator’s patterns of coercive control, advocates the greater inclusion of perpetrators of domestic abuse in child protection assessments, procedures, and social work interventions, engaging and working holistically with both parents and holding men accountable as parents and partners for the abuse and its effects (Mandel and Rankin, 2018). Joint training in Safe and Together™ involving CJSW, Caledonian workers, and Children and Families Social Work services has been rolled out across some local authorities in Scotland. ‘Situational couple violence’ does not typically involve either partner attempting to gain control over the relationship, with episodes of violence usually sparked by conflict situations; nonetheless, serious violence and harm can still occur (Johnson, 2008), and any proposed RJ interventions would similarly require robust assessment and skilled management in deciding on the appropriateness of the intervention. Restoring communities From an RJ perspective, what is the role of CJSW in relation to communities? Recent developments in many jurisdictions internationally, including Scotland, England and Wales, emphasise community 8 engagement in CJSW. For instance, the Community Empowerment (Scotland) Act 2015 places a duty on local authorities to take community perspectives into account when designing and delivering public services. This includes partnership working in the creation and management of ‘community justice’ services. As explained by Maglione (2018), these ‘third-way’ or ‘hybrid’ approaches to justice, connecting state and community relations, are compatible with an RJ orientation that encourages participation and empowerment among community members in the delivery of justice. Weaver (2011) describes RJ as a personalised response to crime that places the main stakeholders (the person responsible for the offence, the victim and the community) at the centre of the process. However, McCold (2004) argues that RJ and community justice have some similarities, but important differences. He suggests community justice often involves expanding the criminal justice process to include community representatives, without necessarily involving the person responsible for the offence and the direct victim. The Community Justice (Scotland) Act 2016 requires community justice partners to co-operate in the delivery of criminal justice services in the community. These partners include CJSW, the police, the courts and a range of other statutory and third sector bodies. The emphasis on community justice, which is connected to the wider reform of social services in order to increase community participation (Christie, 2011), could include the greater provision of RJ services and higher levels of inclusion among those responsible for and affected by crime regarding the response to crime; indeed, victim involvement is a form of community engagement. For public services to move beyond formal state representatives in justice processes, to include lay representatives of the community, we must reimagine existing models of community partnership. McCold (2000) describes three main groups from the ‘community’ that could be represented in restorative processes: 1) ‘secondary victims’ who have suffered via their personal relationship with the person responsible for the offence or the victim; 2) ‘communities of support’, which includes people who care about one of the people but were not harmed by the offence; and 3) representatives from the local community who do not personally know the individuals, but have a more general concern about crime in the locality. These three groups will have different needs and reasons for being involved in restorative processes. Secondary victims may have their own legitimate grievances that ought to be addressed through the restorative processes whereas people representing a community of support may take part to aid the person responsible for or harmed by the offence. It may also be appropriate to have a representative from a ‘community of interest’. For instance, if the offence was racially motivated, the representative could be from the victim’s ethnic group; if the victim was targeted due to their sexuality, then a representative from a group by and for people who are gay or bisexual may be appropriate. Ultimately, the people affected by the offence should have some say in which communities best represent them. Any of these community representatives could play a role in helping the person with processes of integration and change (e.g., in terms of providing ongoing personal support or connecting with employment opportunities). Braithwaite and Mugford (1994) suggest that RJ stands a greater chance of facilitating desistance from crime if the people who take part are known to the person responsible for the offence. What exactly is the purpose of involving community representatives? Rosenblatt (2018: 294) identifies three roles for community in RJ: 1. it should have a say in what reparation the offender should undergo to restore the victimised community; 2. as the victimised community, it should benefit from this reparation; 3. and it should be able to support the reintegration of offenders into the community as positive, contributing members. However, in her examination of community involvement in ‘youth offender panels’ in England and Wales, she found that community representatives tended not to bring creative ideas to the discussion of reparation and they were less well placed than the professionals to support 9 participants with reintegration. Crawford (2002) suggested that community involvement in RJ could improve civil society’s response to crime; however, he highlighted that managerial and procedural constraints on youth offender panels limited this potential. In Northern Ireland, Chapman (2012) illustrated that community restorative justice could be effective if it was defined as ‘the skilful facilitation of restorative processes rather than the management and control of outcomes’, drawing on the assets of community-based facilitators while resisting the colonisation of processes by the state. CJSW practitioners ought to consider the value and potential of including community representation in restorative processes, but be aware that involvement does not ensure that restorative outcomes will occur. Discussion: Restorative Justice Informed Criminal Justice Social Work In her role as a criminal justice social worker in Scotland, the second author has come across men and women who wish to offer an apology and explain their actions to the people they have harmed. They are currently unable to do so because no mechanism exists for facilitating this contact in this jurisdiction. If we apply an RJ perspective to CJSW, particularly the roles of supervising people on community sentences or on licence following imprisonment, how does this transform our views of these practices? We argue the aim of supervision is re-envisioned to include helping people reflect on ways of making amends. Practice is magnified to include facilitating dialogue between people responsible for harm and the people they have harmed. The focus on reparative acts is recalibrated so that the potential for relevant and meaningful gestures are examined and supported. Reintegration is viewed as a process of reconciling an individual with their community. Reflecting on making amends A restorative approach to CJSW would include an explicit consideration of what it means to make amends for offending behaviour. This goes beyond the sentence. It is not the punishment forced upon the individual. It involves the person responsible for the harm voluntarily considering what it means to make up for their harmful acts. As moral repair (Walker, 2006; Ward and Moreton, 2008), the person responsible for the offence would consider what they could say or do to make amends. While the primary focus would be on the main offence, it could include other criminal (and non- criminal) harm they caused or suffered. The practice would be trauma-informed, recognising wrongs where they lay, while encouraging personal responsibility and with an eye to the future. In Scotland, the four ‘interventions’ of CJSW are restrictions, rehabilitation, reparation and reintegration (Scottish Government, 2010a); to these it would add ‘restoration’. This ‘partly-restorative’ groundwork could provide the basis for dialogue with the person harmed. Facilitating dialogue In bringing an RJ perspective, the biggest change to CJSW practice would be direct engagement with victims of crime and facilitating dialogue between them and the people who harmed them. Duff (2003: 181) argues that ‘probation officers’ should act as ‘mediators between offenders, victims and the wider community’. As argued by Daniels (2013: 304), this would require a ‘recalibration of focus to include the victim.’ This would be a significant extension of the nature and reach of CJSW services, requiring new knowledge and skills. However, as we have argued, this would be a logical extension, building on much of the values and expertise that social workers already possess. By increasing the field of vision to include victims of crime, CJSW services would no longer be limited to working on behalf of victims (and potential future victims), but directly working with victims. For the person under supervision, this dialogue becomes an opportunity to learn about the harm they have caused, apologise and offer to make amends. For the person harmed, they are able to ask questions, hear answers, discuss and agree what should be done to make things right, and forgive if they wish. The 10 outcomes of this discussion become raw material for the parallel processes of desistance from crime and recovery from harm. The victim’s words become a tool for breaking through defence mechanisms that downplay the extent or culpability of the harm caused. Practitioners can point to the person’s voluntary engagement in RJ, and the victim’s recognition of their good intentions, to reaffirm their moral orientation. They can remind the person of the commitments they have made as a way to keep them on track. For the victim, having the person take responsibility for the offence could be used in therapeutic interventions to reduce self-blame. Their involvement in RJ can be used by practitioners supporting the victim to illustrate their empowerment and help them reimagine a future that is less dominated by the person who did them wrong. Meaningful reparation Bazemore and Maloney (1994: 30) outlined principles for unpaid work informed by RJ: 1. Ensure that the service meets a clearly defined need and that this need is obvious to offenders 2. The service activity should at least symbolically link offender with offense and victims, and, whenever possible, community service should be performed in the offender's neighborhood 3. The activity should bring offender and conventional adults together 4. Probation staff and community service supervisors should view offenders as resources and focus on outcomes 5. Involve offenders in planning and executing projects 6. Provide for a sense of accomplishment, closure, and community recognition Unpaid work as it currently operates in Scotland could meet all of these principles, and may meet them in some cases already. However, research on the use of unpaid work suggests that that consultation with communities is fragmented, that the benefits are not routinely communicated to the public, and that most unpaid work involves group cleaning, repair activities or workshop placements (Scottish Government, 2015), all of which limits its potential to meet these principles. Older research by Curran, MacQueen, Whyte and Boyle (2007) highlighted the challenges of making unpaid work relevant to the original offence, meaningful as a way of making amends or productive in terms of developing skills. McIvor (2016) emphasises that unpaid work has a greater impact on attitudes and behaviours related to offending when the people undertaking it feel it is rewarding, when they gain skills by it and when they see the benefits it provides to others. A restorative approach to unpaid work would involve greater effort to make the work undertaken meaningful in relation to the original offence and beneficial for those undertaking it, victims of crime and communities. Reintegration as reconciliation McNeill (2012) argued there are four forms of rehabilitation: personal, social, moral and legal. CJSW focuses on the personal dimensions; the individual and psychological risks, needs and strengths that relate to offending behaviour. It may also address social dimensions, such as helping someone change or extend their social relationships. RJ processes and reparative tasks can address the moral dimensions, as people reflect on and make amends for the harm caused. Legal rehabilitation means ensuring that punishment ends, permitting people to move on with their lives, and even performing ‘reintegration rituals’ that formally recognise the individual has made amends for their offence and is welcomed back into society (Maruna, 2011). This perspective highlights that reintegration is two- way; the onus is not only on the person who committed the offence, but there are also obligations among others in society (Kirkwood and McNeill, 2015). Reintegration is therefore also reconciliation; sometimes between the person who committed the offence and those they directly harmed, but also with wider social circles and society as a whole. A restorative approach to reintegration means engaging with these wider needs and obligations. 11 Bazemore (1998) describes this process as ‘earned redemption’: those who have done wrong should make amends, and those who have made amends should be supported back into society. RJ can help do this through engaging with the micro communities relevant to individuals, such as family and friends, who can participate in constructive dialogue and become part of the process of reintegration. Victims of crime and community representatives can provide symbolic or practical gestures of reintegration, such as saying they appreciate an apology, recognising the value of reparations made, emphasising the potential they see in the individual’s future, rebuilding damaged relationships, creating friendships, or connecting with volunteering and employment opportunities. This process becomes part of the practical and symbolic process of desistance, as someone is supported to overcome barriers to change, build hope, identify a pro-social identity for themselves and have this potential recognised by others (McNeill, 2006). Final remarks Although we focused on the specific case of Scotland, we expect that there will be similarities in other jurisdictions internationally, although the detail how of such services operate will vary. Viewing criminal justice social work through an RJ lens allows us to see how it could be changed in ways that extend its ability to achieve existing aims and enhance its role in relation to victims of crime and communities. CJSW could therefore incorporate greater RJ processes and practices – especially the facilitation of dialogue between those responsible and harmed by crime – as well as shifting the whole system in the direction of restorative outcomes. However, introducing greater RJ processes into the criminal justice system has the potential to add additional burdens onto those subject to criminal justice, threatening principles of proportionality (Ashworth, 2002; Masson and Österman, 2017). This can be managed through the appropriate use of RJ within diversion from prosecution, pre-sentencing and post-sentencing processes (Kirkwood, 2018b). Within diversion, RJ can be used as an alternative to more burdensome or punitive responses. In pre-sentencing, an RJ process could inform the sentence, with sentencers ensuring outcomes remain proportionate. While people are on community sentences or supervision, voluntary engagement in RJ processes could take the place of some existing activities. Specifically, in Scotland, those sentenced to a Community Payback Order with a requirement to undertake unpaid work can spend some of this time on ‘other activities’, which could be RJ processes, without adding to the overall time spent completing the order (Kirkwood, 2018b). However, the institutionalisation of RJ can lead to problems, particularly the corruption and dilution of processes (Wood and Suzuki, 2016); therefore any expansion in the use of RJ needs to be monitored to ensure it is ethical, safe and effective. As stated by Daniels (2013), the overall intention is to shift practice a bit further along the RJ continuum. 12 References Anderson SE (2016) The value of ‘bearing witness’ to desistance. Probation Journal 63(4): 408–424. DOI: 10.1177/0264550516664146. Armstrong J (2012) Factors Contributing to Victims’ Satisfaction with Restorative Justice Practice: A Qualitative Examination. British Journal of Community Justice 10(2): 39–54. Ashworth A (2002) Responsibilities, rights and restorative justice. British Journal of Criminology 42(3): 578–595. DOI: 10.1093/bjc/42.3.578. Bazemore G (1998) Restorative Justice and Earned Redemption. American Behavioral Scientist 41(6): 768–813. DOI: 10.1177/0002764298041006003. Bazemore G and Maloney D (1994) Rehabilitating Community Service Toward Restorative Service Sanctions in a Balanced Justice System. Federal Probation 58: 24–35. Bonta J and Andrews DA (2017) The Psychology of Criminal Conduct. 6th ed. New York: Routledge. Braithwaite J (1989) Crime, Shame and Reintegration. New York: Cambridge University Press. Braithwaite J and Mugford S (1994) Conditions of successful reintegration ceremonies: Dealing with juvenile offenders. British Journal of Criminology 34(2): 139–171. DOI: 10.1111/j.1745- 9133.2012.00786.x. Chadwick N, Dewolf A and Serin R (2015) Effectively Training Community Supervision Officers: A Meta-Analytic Review of the Impact on Offender Outcome. Criminal Justice and Behavior 42(10): 977–989. DOI: 10.1177/0093854815595661. Chapman T (2012) The Problem of Community in a Justice System in Transition: The Case of Community Restorative Justice in Northern Ireland. International Criminal Law Review 12(3): 573–588. DOI: 10.1163/157181212x648815. Chapman T and Chapman A (2016) Forgiveness in restorative justice: Experienced but not heard? Oxford Journal of Law and Religion 5(1): 135–152. DOI: 10.1093/ojlr/rwv066. Christie C (2011) Commission on the future delivery of public services. Available at: http://www.gov.scot/Resource/Doc/352649/0118638.pdf. Christie N (1977) Conflicts as property. British Journal of Criminology 17(1): 1–15. Crawford A (2002) Recent Developments in Restorative Justice for Young People in England and Wales: Community Participation and Representation. British Journal of Criminology 42(3): 476– 495. DOI: 10.1093/bjc/42.3.476. Curran J, MacQueen S, Whyte B, et al. (2007) ‘Forced to make amends’: An evaluation of the community reparation order pilots. Edinburgh. Available at: http://www.sccjr.ac.uk/wp- content/uploads/2010/01/Forced_to_make_amends.pdf. Daly K (2006) Restorative justice and sexual assault: An archival study of court and conference cases. British Journal of Criminology 46(2): 334–356. DOI: 10.1093/bjc/azi071. Daly K (2016) What is Restorative Justice? Fresh Answers to a Vexed Question. Victims & Offenders 11(1): 9–29. DOI: 10.1080/15564886.2015.1107797. Daniels G (2013) Restorative justice: Changing the paradigm. Probation Journal 60(3): 302–315. DOI: 10.1177/0264550513493370. Duff RA (2003) Probation, Punishment And Restorative Justice: Should Al Turism Be Engaged in Punishment? The Howard Journal 42(2): 181–197. Johnson MP (2008) A Typology of Domestic Violence: Intimate Terrorism, Violent Resistance, and Situational Couple Violence. Boston: Northeastern University Press. Kirkwood S (2018a) Criminal Justice Social Work. In: Cree VE and Smith M (eds) Social Work in a Changing Scotland. New York: Routledge, pp. 141–150. Kirkwood S (2018b) Iriss insight: Restorative Justice. Glasgow. DOI: 10.4135/9781452229300.n1601. Kirkwood S and McNeill F (2015) Integration and reintegration: Comparing pathways to citizenship through asylum and criminal justice. Criminology and Criminal Justice 15(5): 511–526. Available at: http://crj.sagepub.com/content/15/5/511. Koss MP (2014) The RESTORE Program of Restorative Justice for Sex Crimes: Vision, Process, and 13 Outcomes. Journal of Interpersonal Violence 29(9): 1623–1660. DOI: 10.1177/0886260513511537. Latimer J, Dowden C and Muise D (2005) The Effectiveness of Restorative Justice Practices: A Meta- Analysis. The Prison Journal 85(2): 127–144. DOI: 10.1177/0032885505276969. London R (2003) The restoration of trust: Bringing restorative justice from the margins to the mainstream. Criminal Justice Studies 16(3): 175–195. DOI: 10.1080/0888431032000151844. Macrae R (2014) The Caledonian System: An integrated approach to address men’s domestic violence and to improve the lives of women, children and men. Ending Men’s Violence Against Women and Children (Autumn): 37–58. Maglione G (2018) The political rationality of restorative justice. Theoretical Criminology. DOI: 10.1177/1362480618756364. Mandel D and Rankin H (2018) Working with Men as Parents: Becoming Father-Inclusive to Improve Child Welfare Outcomes in Domestic Violence Cases. Columbus, OH: Family and Youth Law Center, Capital University Law School. Marsh F and Wager NM (2015) Restorative justice in cases of sexual violence: Exploring the views of the public and survivors. Probation Journal 62(4): 336–356. DOI: 10.1177/0264550515619571. Marshall T (1999) Restorative Justice: An overview. London. Maruna S (2001) Making Good: How Ex-Convicts Reform and Rebuild Their Lives. Washington DC, USA: American Psychological Association. Maruna S (2006) Who Owns Resettlement? Towards Restorative Re-Integration. British Journal of Community Justice 4(2): 23–34. Maruna S (2011) Reentry as a rite of passage. Punishment and Society 13(1): 3–28. DOI: 10.1177/1462474510385641. Maruna S and Farrall S (2004) Desistance from crime: A theoretical reformulation. Kölner Zeitschrift für Soziologie und Sozialpsychologie 43: 171–194. Masson I and Österman L (2017) Working with female offenders in restorative justice frameworks. Probation Journal 64(4): 354–371. DOI: 10.1177/0264550517728784. McCold P (2000) Toward a holistic vision of restorative juvenile justice: A reply to the Maximalist model. Contemporary Justice Review 3(4): 357–414. McCold P (2004) Paradigm Muddle: The Threat to Restorative Justice Posed by Its Merger with Community Justice. Contemporary Justice Review 7(1): 13–35. DOI: 10.1080/1028258042000211987. McGlynn C, Westmarland N and Godden N (2012) ‘I Just Wanted Him to Hear Me’: Sexual Violence and the Possibilities of Restorative Justice. Journal of Law and Society 39(2): 213–240. DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-6478.2012.00579.x. McIvor G (2016) What Is the Impact of Community Service? In: McNeill F, Durnescu I, and Butter R (eds) Probation: 12 Essential Questions. London: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 107–128. McNeill F (2006) A desistance paradigm for offender management. Criminology and Criminal Justice 6(1): 39–62. DOI: 10.1177/1748895806060666. McNeill F (2009) What works and what’s just? European Journal of Probation 1(1): 21–40. DOI: 10.1177/206622030900100103. McNeill F (2012) Four forms of ‘offender’ rehabilitation: Towards an interdisciplinary perspective. Legal and Criminological Psychology 17(1): 18–36. DOI: 10.1111/j.2044-8333.2011.02039.x. McNeill F and Beyens K (2014) Offender Supervision in Europe. McNeill F and Beyens K (eds). Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave Macmillan. McNeill F, Batchelor S, Burnett R, et al. (2005) 21st Century Social Work: Reducing Re-Offending: Key Practice Skills. Social Work. Edinburgh: Scottish Executive. Available at: http://eprints.gla.ac.uk/33796/. Morris A (2002) Critiquing the Critics: A Brief Response to Critics of Restorative Justice. British Journal of Criminology 42(3): 596–615. DOI: 10.1093/bjc/42.3.596. Paternoster R, Bachman R, Kerrison E, et al. (2016) Desistance from crime and identity: An empirical 14 test with survival time. Criminal Justice and Behavior 43(9): 1204–1224. DOI: 10.1177/0093854816651905. Pemberton A (2007) Taking Victims Seriously in Restorative Justice. International Perspectives in Victimology 3(1): 4–14. Pemberton A, Aarten PG and Mulder E (2018) Stories as property: Narrative ownership as a key concept in victims’ experiences with criminal justice. Criminology & Criminal Justice. DOI: 10.1177/1748895818778320. Phelps MS (2016) Mass probation: Toward a more robust theory of state variation in punishment. Punishment & Society 19(1): 53–73. DOI: 10.1177/1462474516649174. Roach K (2000) Changing punishment at the turn of the century: Restorative justice on the rise. Canadian Journal of Criminology 42: 249–280. Robinson G and Shapland J (2008) Reducing recidivism: A task for restorative justice? British Journal of Criminology 48(3): 337–358. DOI: 10.1093/bjc/azn002. Rocque M, Posick C and Paternoster R (2016) Identities through time: An exploration of identity change as a cause of desistance. Justice Quarterly 33(1). Routledge: 45–72. DOI: 10.1080/07418825.2014.894111. Rosenblatt FF (2018) Community involvement in restorative justice: lessons from an English and Welsh case study on youth offender panels. Restorative Justice: An International Journal 2(3): 280–301. DOI: 10.5235/20504721.2.3.280. Scottish Government (2004) National Objectives for Social Work Services in the Criminal Justice System. Edinburgh. Available at: http://www.gov.scot/Publications/2004/12/20471/49284. Scottish Government (2010a) National Outcomes and Standards for Social Work Services in the Criminal Justice System: Community Payback Orders Practice Guidance. Edinburgh. Available at: http://www.gov.scot/Resource/Doc/344043/0114450.pdf. Scottish Government (2010b) National Outcomes and Standards for Social Work Services in the Criminal Justice System. Edinburgh: The Scottish Government. Available at: http://www.gov.scot/resource/doc/925/0103556.pdf. Scottish Government (2015) Evaluation of Community Payback Orders, Criminal Justice Social Work Reports and the Presumption Against Short Sentences. Available at: http://www.gov.scot/Resource/0047/00472126.pdf. Scottish Government (2017) Guidance for the Delivery of Restorative Justice in Scotland. Edinburgh. Available at: http://www.gov.scot/Publications/2017/10/8454. Scottish Government (2018a) Criminal Proceedings in Scotland, 2016-17. Edinburgh. Available at: https://gov.scot/Publications/2018/02/7427. Scottish Government (2018b) Delivering for Today, Investing for Tomorrow: The Government’s Programme for Scotland 2018-19. Edinburgh: Scottish Government. Available at: https://beta.gov.scot/publications/delivering-today-investing-tomorrow-governments- programme-scotland-2018-19/. Scottish Government (2019) Restorative justice action plan. Edinburgh. Available at: https://www.gov.scot/publications/restorative-justice-action-plan/. Sen R, Morris K, Burford G, et al. (2018) ‘When you’re sitting in the room with two people one of whom… has bashed the hell out of the other’: Possibilities and challenges in the use of FGCs and restorative approaches following domestic violence. Children and Youth Services Review 88: 441–449. DOI: 10.1016/j.childyouth.2018.03.027. Shapland J, Atkinson A, Atkinson H, et al. (2008) Does restorative justice affect reconviction?: The fourth report from the evaluation of three schemes. Sherman LW and Strang H (2007) Restorative justice: The evidence. London. Available at: http://www.iirp.edu/pdf/RJ_full_report.pdf. Strang H, Sherman LW, Mayo-Wilson E, et al. (2013) Restorative justice conferencing (RJC) using face-to-face meetings of offenders and victims: Effects on offender recidivism and victim satisfaction: A systematic review. Oslo. DOI: 10.4073/csr.2013.12. 15 Thomson L (2017) Review of Victim Care in the Justice Sector in Scotland. Trotter C (2014) Working with Involuntary Clients: A Guide to Practice. 3rd ed. Abingdon, Oxon, UK: Routledge. Walgrave L (2000) How pure can a maximalist approach to restorative justice remain? Or can a purist model of restorative justice become maximalist? Contemporary Justice Review 3(4): 415–432. Walker MU (2006) Moral Repair: Reconstructing Moral Relations after Wrongdoing. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Ward T and Moreton G (2008) Moral Repair With Offenders. Sexual Abuse: A Journal of Research and Treatment 20(3): 305–322. DOI: 10.1177/1079063208322423. Ward T, Gannon TA and Fortune C-A (2015) Restorative Justice–Informed Moral Acquaintance: Resolving the Dual Role Problem in Correctional and Forensic Practice. Criminal Justice and Behavior 42(1): 45–57. DOI: 10.1177/0093854814550026. Ward T, Fox KJ and Garber M (2015) Restorative justice, offender rehabilitation and desistance. Restorative Justice 2(1): 24–42. DOI: 10.5235/20504721.2.1.24. Weaver B (2011) Co-Producing Community Justice: The Transformative Potential of Personalisation for Penal Sanctions. British Journal of Social Work 41: 1038–1057. Whyte B and Kearney N (2017) Peacebuilding and RiSC: Elements of a Scottish model for restorative practices in serious crime. Scottish Justice Matters 5(1): 11–12. Wood WR and Suzuki M (2016) Four Challenges in the Future of Restorative Justice. Victims & Offenders 11(1). Routledge: 149–172. DOI: 10.1080/15564886.2016.1145610. World Prison Brief (2018) Highest to lowest prison population rate. Available at: http://prisonstudies.org/highest-to-lowest/prison_population_rate (accessed 27 July 2018). Zehr H (1991) Changing Lenses: New Focus for Crime and Justice. Scottsdale, PA: Herald Press. work_2mpqjp5cjjgtxfrz5zrf5qt3s4 ---- Training police for procedural justice Wesley G. Skogan & Maarten Van Craen & Cari Hennessy # Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014 Abstract Objectives This paper reports the findings of an evaluation of a police training program on the principles of procedural justice. This training was part of a larger organizational change strategy aimed at improving the relationship between the police and the public in Chicago. Methods The paper reports on the findings of two studies. The short-term effects study was a quasi-experimental test of the immediate effectiveness of the training conducted at the police academy. A longer-term effects study examined the subsequent views of trainees and a comparison group, officers who had not yet been to training. Statistical controls were used to increase confidence in the findings of the second study, which was based on observational data. Results In the short term, training increased officer support for all of the procedural justice dimensions included in the experiment. Post-training, officers were more likely to endorse the importance of giving citizens a voice, granting them dignity and respect, demonstrating neutrality, and (with the least enthusiasm) trusting them to do the right thing. All of the effects of training were strong, with standardized effect sizes ranging from 1.2 to 1.6. Longer-term, officers who had attended the procedural justice work- shop continued to be more supportive of three of the four procedural justice principles introduced in training; the effect of training on trust was not statistically significant. Conclusions There has been little systematic research on police training. This paper concludes that it can play a role in improving police–community relations. It also presents a discussion of some of the limitations of a training-based organizational change strategy. J Exp Criminol DOI 10.1007/s11292-014-9223-6 W. G. Skogan (*): C. Hennessy Institute for Policy Research, Northwestern University, 2040 Sheridan Road, Evanston, IL, USA e-mail: skogan@northwestern.edu C. Hennessy e-mail: cari.hennessy@northwestern.edu M. Van Craen Leuven Institute of Criminology (LINC), University of Leuven, Hooverplein 10, 3000 Leuven, Belgium e-mail: maarten.vancraen@law.kuleuven.be Author's personal copy Keywords Quasi-experiment . Survey. Police training . Procedural justice . Neutrality. Respect . Voice . Trust A very large body of research has demonstrated the importance of procedural justice in shaping the legitimacy of police in the eyes of the public. We know that the public is concerned that police decisions are made fairly and evenhandedly, that citizens are treated respectfully and given a chance to voice their views, and that officers are thought to abide by the rules that govern their behavior (for reports of research and reviews see Jackson et al. 2013; Mazerolle et al. 2013a; Murphy et al. 2008; Tyler and Jackson 2013). However, there has been almost no research at all regarding how the police can be encouraged to incorporate the principles of procedural justice in their routine interactions with the public. This project examined an initiative by the Chicago Police Department to reshape its relationship with the community by training officers in the principles of procedural justice. Training began in mid-2012 and concluded in September 2013. In total, about 8,700 serving officers, 230 new recruits, many of the department’s civilian employees, and some community members involved in policing issues were trained. The research team conducted two studies evaluating this effort. The shorter-term effects study was a quasi-experimental test of the immediate effectiveness of the training conducted at the academy. A longer-term effects study followed, with inter- views of trainees and a comparison group, officers who had not yet been to training. Statistical controls were used to increase confidence in the findings of the long-term effects study. In addition, we monitored training sessions and interviewed trainers, trainees, and program developers. In the shorter term, training increased officer support for all of the procedural justice dimensions included in the experiment. Post-training, they were more likely to endorse the importance of giving citizens a voice, granting them dignity and respect, demon- strating neutrality, and (with the least enthusiasm) trusting them to do the right thing. All of the effects of training were strong, based on standardized effect size measures. Longer-term, officers who had attended the procedural justice workshop continued to be more supportive of three of the four procedural justice principles introduced in training, compared to officers who had not yet been sent to training. Background on police training We know virtually nothing about the short- or long-term effects associated with police training of any type. A committee established by the National Research Council to evaluate the state of policing in the United States found that there were “scarcely more than a handful of studies” on the effects of training, and that police training and education were being offered without scientific evidence of their likely effects. The panel concluded “[T]he committee cannot overstate the importance of developing a comprehensive and scientifically rigorous program to learn what is and is not effective in the education and training of police officers” (Skogan and Frydl 2004: 154). There has not been much progress in the decade since that report appeared. Police depart- ments themselves often distribute post-training questionnaires that evaluate practical W.G. Skogan et al. Author's personal copy aspects of the class and the capabilities of the trainers, and they occasionally report “before-and-after” studies of a training class. External researchers have done a bit better, but the volume, quality, and generality of evaluation work on police training has been low. Wheller and Morris’ (2010) review of research on training for the UK National Police Improvement Agency casts a very wide net, incorporating systematic studies of training for “professionals” of all kinds, but did not find much outside the domain of clinical training for health professionals. They located no published exper- imental studies of police training; however, they missed Rosenbaum’s (1987) experi- mental study of training police recruits in how to better handle crime victims. He randomized new recruits into training or an alternative control activity and later assessed their attitudes and behavioral intentions. Virtually no research of any flavor has been done on procedural justice training, despite this being a necessary precursor to turning the theory into practice. The Mazerolle et al. (2013a) systematic review of procedural justice and police legitimacy alludes to the important role that training could play, but did not report a single training study. However, since that time, Wheller et al. (2013) released the findings of an experimental study of procedural justice training. Officers from the Greater Manchester Police Service were randomly assigned to treatment or control groups in order to determine the impact of training on the perceived quality of interactions between the police and crime victims. The training program incorporated elements of procedural justice theory. The evaluation identified positive shifts on four of eight police attitudinal outcomes, and positive effects on trained officers’ scores in role-playing exercises. The perceptions of crime victims who later were served by trained and control-group officers also differed on some measures. In addition, a randomized trial involving police breath-testing roadblocks conducted by Mazerolle et al. (2013b) can be viewed as a test of the ability of officers to follow scripts that activate perceptions of procedural justice during encounters with the public, when they are briefed on how to do so. Chicago’s training program The training program was developed internally, by sworn members of the department’s training staff. The impetus for this effort came from the top of the organization, when a new chief of police arrived with a commitment to imbue his department with the principles of procedural justice. At his initiative, members of the training staff worked with academics (at another university) to develop an outline for a training program. Based on this preliminary plan, the staff identified concepts and findings from the research literature that they could translate into training units. They used the Internet to locate video clips and images that would illustrate key points. Their goal was to present procedural justice principles to officers as tactics that would encourage the public to recognize the police as a legitimate source of authority, resulting in improved officer safety, more compliance with their instructions, and greater cooperation from the public. The training involved officers from every unit of the department. As it progressed, the units sent just a few officers to training each day, so participants trickled into the academy rather than arriving in related batches. Classes of at most 25 officers met with Training police for procedural justice Author's personal copy rotating teams of three trainers for day-long sessions. Unusually for this organization, the classes mixed employees of various ranks, although they attended in civilian clothing to soften the impact of this heterogeneity. Multiple classes were conducted on two shifts; morning watch officers began at 7:00 am, and afternoon and evening watch officers at 3:30 pm, Mondays through Thursdays. The trainers came from diverse backgrounds, and many were working in the field when they were recruited for the job. They had the credible street experience that they needed to convince officers that they knew what they were talking about, and to overcome resistance from those suspecting that the trainers had grown out of touch while working at the academy. The training modules The training day was divided into five modules. Each featured lectures accompanied by PowerPoint slides, video clips, and group exercises. Module 1 introduced the ideas of procedural justice and legitimacy, and how they intersect with the goals of policing. In the ensuing slides and discussion (which the trainers noted were based on research), procedural justice was defined as treating citizens fairly and with respect as human beings. Legitimacy was described as what the police receive in return: a public that views them as entitled to exercise authority in order to maintain order, manage conflicts, and resolve problems in the community. Module 2 featured a discussion of cynicism. This was added to the curriculum in response to issues that arose during the first month of training. A discussion topic was whether cynicism is actually “realism,” or if it exaggerates the actual situation facing officers and serves to drive a wedge between them and the public. During this module, half of the table groups discussed and recorded their views on the question, “What does the community expect from police officers?” The other half of the table groups considered the question, “What do police officers expect from the community?” Module 3 included a more in-depth discussion of procedural justice, and featured research findings from Chicago as well as other cities that supported trainers’ claims about the importance of the components of procedural justice. Most slides also stressed one of the major selling points of the training day, which was that following these principles would ultimately benefit police officers by increasing citizen cooperation, encouraging the public to comply with police instruc- tions, and maximizing officer safety. Module 4 began with a discussion of race and policing in historical context, both in Chicago and around the country. In interviews, the trainers indicated that discussing the role of race in policing proved to be the second hardest “sell” in the curriculum, following only having to convince officers that “legitimacy” should be one of their personal concerns. One trainer described this experience: On the [course] evaluation, somebody said the only thing that I did was show white officers beating up on black people. And I thought that I failed, because if that’s the only thing you remember in 8 h, then I did something wrong. Near the end of module 4 the trainers introduced the idea that there can be a “balance of trade” between police and the community. They argued that good encounters with W.G. Skogan et al. Author's personal copy the police are “deposits” and bad encounters are “withdrawals” from the account balance that they have developed with the community. The final module was a wrapping-up exercise. Participants viewed and discussed a video of a drug arrest in which the officer calmly, politely, and successfully took both a street dealer and his customer into custody. Then, going around the room, each table made a statement about what they had learned in the class. The short-term effects of training The short-term training study introduced a modest quasi-experiment into the routine of the academy. It contrasted the views of officers who took the survey before they began their training with the attitudes of officers who completed the survey at the conclusion of their session. The calendar date was used to assign classes to treatment (after) or control (before) status. Questionnaires were distributed before the class began on odd- numbered days (for example, December 3), and at the end of the class on even- numbered days. The odd-day and even-day questionnaires were identical except for their colors (blue or white), which helped the instructors track their proper administra- tion. As an implementation check, a question on the survey asked trainees if they had completed the questionnaire before or after the session. To enhance compliance with procedures, we ensured that, from the beginning, trainers understood that this was an evaluation of training and not trainers. The study materials did not identify which trainers had conducted a class. One class was misassigned to take the survey after training instead of before, but it was retained in its improper category for this intention- to-treat analysis. Because assignment was by classroom, we examined differences between “be- fore” classes and “after” classes at the classroom level. Over the study period December 2012 to May 2013 the odd-even approach to allocating classrooms created groups that were very similar in terms of their measured characteristics. Table 1 describes some features of the data. In total, 2,681 officers completed the survey (another 0.6 % chose not to participate); they participated in 133 classes, with 67 surveyed before training and 66 after training. The participants split 51–49 % between the two groups. The survey questioned respondents about just two personal factors, their age and the unit in the department to which they were assigned; these questions were included in order to confirm that the treatment and control groups were similar. Table 1 presents the mean and median ages of the treatment and control groups, and the percentage of each group that was assigned to the agency’s patrol division, which is by far the largest. Differences between them proved to be very small and they were not statistically significant. Table 1 Participation in the classroom experiment Number of officers Number of classrooms Mean age Median age Percent in patrol Treatment 1,392 66 42.3 42.5 89.8 Control 1,289 67 42.1 41.8 89.7 Training police for procedural justice Author's personal copy Measuring procedural justice The survey included questions regarding officers’ views of their relationship with the public. Because of time constraints the questionnaires had to be very short; we promised the training academy that it would be one extended page in length. A section at the beginning described the survey and its purpose, and reminded trainees of their rights as human subjects. Officers indicated their assent by continuing on to complete the questionnaire, but they were not required to do so (this section was approved by the university’s human subjects committee). The survey next presented officers with statements to which they could respond, using four point response scales that ranged from “agree strongly” and “agree” to “disagree” and “disagree strongly.” The statements were designed to reflect four procedural justice concepts that were emphasized at training (for an extensive discus- sion of these dimensions see Hinds and Murphy 2007, and Bradford 2011). How to address them in this study was an open question. Most procedural justice research has focused on the public’s view of the police, and almost all procedural justice research involving the police has asked how they are being treated by their own organizations and leaders (see, for example, Tyler et al. 2007). By contrast, measuring officers’ views of how they should be treating members of the public, using questions reflecting the dimensions of procedural justice theory, was unexplored territory. The lack of a research tradition in this area required the evaluation team to craft new questions that promised to address the components of the theory. The questions had to be phrased in ways that generated variance in officers’ responses. Some of the assertions were stated in such a way that agreement indicated support for procedural justice principles, while others called for disagreement by those who supported this view. This strategy was used to keep them alert to the content of the questions. The questions assigned to each dimension were also scattered throughout the survey, to discourage inattentive responses. The study team had to wait until the survey was complete to set the item responses that were measuring the attitudinal dimension. Responses to multiple questions were combined to create scale scores when they were single factored, and these factors explained a large proportion of the variance in the combined items. Neutrality calls for consistency and even-handedness in decision making across persons (equal treatment for all) and across time (the same procedures are followed every time). Neutral decisions are reasoned, objective and factually driven, and they respect rules and legal principles. In training, officers were encouraged to make it clear to those they encountered that they were acting in this way. Neutrality was measured by responses to four statements: “It is important to give everyone a good reason why we are stopping them, even if there is no need,” “If people ask why we are treating them as we are, we should stop and explain,” “When dealing with citizens’ concerns, officers need to explain what will happen next, when they are done at the scene,” and “It is very important that officers appear neutral in their application of legal rules.” Responses to these statements were correlated an average of +.34. The Alpha reliability for this scale was .68. Voice (sometimes this is referred to as “participation”) involves giving citizens an opportunity to describe their situation and express their opinions about a problem (to “tell their side of the story”) while officers are deciding what to do. Voice was measured W.G. Skogan et al. Author's personal copy by responses to two statements: “Listening and talking to people is a good way to take charge of situations,” and “Officers need to show an honest interest in what people have to say, even if it is not going to change anything.” The items in the summary voice scale were correlated an average of +.36, and the Alpha reliability for the resulting scale was .53. Respect encompasses treating citizens with dignity, acting politely, and granting them other routine interactional signs of respect. Because they are police officers, it is also important that they evidence concern about respecting people’s rights, Respect was measured by responses to three statements: “People should be treated with respect regardless of their attitude,” “Officers should at all times treat people they encounter with dignity and respect,” and “It is important that we remind people they have rights and that we appear to follow them.” The items in the summary respect scale were correlated an average of +.40. The Alpha reliability for this scale was .69. Trust is evidenced when officers treat citizens as if they can be trusted to do the right thing and demonstrate that they are acting on behalf of the best interests of the people they are dealing with. Trust was measured by responses to: “Police have enough trust in the public for them to work together effectively,” and “Officers should treat citizens as if they can be trusted to do the right thing.” Responses to these statements were correlated +.30. The Alpha reliability for this scale was .46. Results of study 1 The statistical findings are summarized in Table 2. The results were positive; there were substantial differences between the treatment and control classrooms for all four dimensions of procedural justice. Table 2 presents mean scale scores and their standard deviations for all four measures, for both treatment conditions. All of the differences described there were statistically significant. The table presents standardized effect sizes (Cohen’s d) that ranged from 1.4 to 1.6. Effect sizes in this range were classified as “strong” by Cohen (1988: 287 and Table 8.2.2). Lipsey (1990) seconded this classification, based on his meta-analysis of 186 meta-analyses of intervention studies. The table also reports correlations between treatment and outcome (Eta Squared); these ranged from .34 to .45, which Cohen translated as signaling a “large” effect. Finally, Table 2 also summarizes the results of a multi-level analysis—the percentage of the variance in the outcome measures that was explained by classroom-level treatment or control status. These ranged from 6 to 10 %, and all were statistically significant. The effects of training can also be seen in the data. Figure 1 compares treatment and control classrooms on the scores created by combining responses to the questions measuring each procedural justice concept. Each symbol in Fig. 1 represents the data for a classroom in the study, divided into treatment and control groups. The “before” dots illustrate average scores for the 67 classrooms surveyed before training, while the “after” dots identify averages for the 66 post-training classes. The dots have been randomly “jittered” to the left and right, in order to visually expose any overlapping class scores. The regression lines presented in Fig. 1 pass through the means of each cluster, highlighting differences between the groups. Officers were most supportive of citizens’ right to exercise voice. They gave the highest endorsement to the view that “Listening and talking to people is a good way Training police for procedural justice Author's personal copy to take charge of situations”; 48 % agreed strongly with this statement. This position reflects very practical police wisdom regarding how they can get through their day safely, and the trainers frequently reminded officers of the safety benefits of adopting procedural justice approaches to dealing with the public. Classroom scores on the composite measure of participation are presented at the right of Fig. 1, and they were the highest both before and after training. As Fig. 1 illustrates, support for citizen participation went up, on average, following training. Table 2 Summary of experimental findings Mean Standard deviation Significance Cohen’s d eta squared Classroom level R-sq Neutrality Treatment 3.1846 .12277 .00 1.60 .40 9 % Control 2.9908 .1177 Respect Treatment 3.1492 .14700 .00 1.49 .36 8 % Control 2.9331 .14338 Trust Treatment 2.7995 .17898 .00 1.65 .41 10 % Control 2.5217 .15634 Voice Treatment 3.3325 .11764 .00 1.42 .34 6 % Control 3.1635 .12032 66 treatment and 67 control classrooms in every comparison Fig. 1 Four dimensions of procedural justice, before and after training W.G. Skogan et al. Author's personal copy In class, officers expressed the least enthusiasm for the procedural justice concept of “trust.” The classroom-level trust scores presented in Fig. 1 are visibly lower than support for the other procedural justice concepts in this group. Officers were most supportive of the view that “Officers should treat citizens as if they can be trusted to do the right thing”; 23 % agreed strongly with this statement. On the other hand, 57 % disagreed with the view that “Police have enough trust in the public for them to work together effectively.” However, before-after differences in trust resembled those for the other dimensions of procedural justice, and the average difference between the two groups was statistically significant. Notably, the largest gain scores (the differences between the treatment and control groups) were for trust; this can also be seen in the more sharply sloping regression line linking the before and after means for trust. Reflecting this, the standardized measure of treatment effect was the largest for trust. Officers’ views of trust may have increased the most because they were relatively low to start with, lending more room for improvement. Between trust and voice lay measures of neutrality and respect. For neutrality, officers gave the most support to the view that “It is very important that officers appear neutral in their application of legal rules”; 33 % agreed with this statement. On the other hand, only 13 % agreed strongly with the view that “When dealing with citizens’ concerns, officers need to explain what will happen next, when they are done at the scene.” However, the correspondence between officers’ reactions to all four statements measuring neutrality was strong; the correlation between the most and least supported views was +.47. The effect of training on officers’ views of neutrality was the second strongest in this set, based on the Cohen’s d reported in Table 2. When it came to support for the concept of treating citizens with respect, only 15 % agreed strongly that “People should be treated with respect regardless of their attitude.” In contrast, 40 % endorsed strongly the idea that “Officers should at all times treat people they encounter with dignity and respect.” Although these were the most divergent items, these responses were correlated +.49. The composite respect measure also shifted significantly between experimental and control classrooms, in response to training. In summary, we found that training increased officer support for all of the procedural justice dimensions measured in the experiment. Post-training they were more likely to endorse the importance of giving citizens a voice, granting them dignity and respect, demonstrating their neutrality and placing some trust in the good intentions of the public. The longer-term effects of training The next question was, did the effects of training persist post-classroom? Studies conducted in police training academies have tracked officers’ views of community policing, and they do not portend well in this regard. In a typical tracking study, Haarr (2001) distributed questionnaires to police recruits over the course of their early career. She found they grew more positive about community policing and problem solving during their stay at the training academy, but that this support began to dissipate during their field training. Their views grew less positive still during their subsequent proba- tionary period. Training police for procedural justice Author's personal copy To probe the persistence question, the longer-term effects of training were examined in a survey of randomly selected officers. This survey began well into the training period, so that some responding officers would have attended training but others would have not yet been sent. A question in the survey identified those who had already participated in the procedural justice workshop and those who had not yet attended. This measure was used, along with statistical adjustments, to examine training-related differences in officers’ views of procedural justice. The survey The survey was conducted in each of the city’s 22 police district stations. At each station we randomly selected Police Officers (the bottom rank) and Sergeants in fixed proportions from the current duty roster. They were also spread proportion- ally across shifts. Sampled employees were notified of their opportunity to participate in the survey through an administrative sergeant. Roll call presenta- tions, flyers, and wall posters, and an offer of coffee and donuts were used to promote participation by those selected, who remained anonymous to the research team until (and if) they appeared. The survey was presented to respondents on laptop computers that the research team set up in stationhouse conference rooms. This ensured that no one could hear their responses to the questions, and that they could proceed at their own pace. The survey included 120 questions, and took at average of 25 min to complete. The survey team made repeat visits to each district, around the clock, until the number of interviews targeted there was completed. The overall response rate was about 28 %. A total of 714 police officers and sergeants were interviewed. The results could be weighted to ensure that the distribution of respondents matched that of the universe of officers serving in the districts, but doing so did not change any of the results presented here. Therefore, the original, unweighted results are presented. Assessing the impact of training In the district survey, 67 % of those interviewed indicated that they had attended “the all-day training workshop on procedural justice and legitimacy at the Acad- emy.” Because of the timing of the district survey, officers could have participated in the workshop as long as 10 months in the past, or as recently as the week before; the timing of their involvement is unknown. This raises the possibility that factors having to do with how early in the queue officers were sent to training could be confounded with any effects of the training itself on their views. This is a real possibility in any non-randomized research on training, if trainees are volun- teers, chosen for their special characteristics, or even selected for their presumed readiness for training. If this is the case, factors related to their selection, rather than the training they received, could account for their later enthusiasm for the topic. However, there are reasons not to fear this kind of contamination here. Officers in the control group identified in the district survey differed because they had not yet been trained; instead, they were further back in the queue. They were not volunteers; the goal of the process was to train everyone, especially in the patrol division. The bureaucratic process that sent daily quotas of officers to W.G. Skogan et al. Author's personal copy training was quite indifferent to their personal characteristics. By design, each district was instructed to send just a few officers to training each day, so partic- ipants trickled into the Academy rather than arriving in related batches. Officers whose turn was to come later, after the follow-up study was completed, were serving in the same districts and working the same shifts as those somewhat closer to the head of the line. As an additional precaution, we also used propensity score adjustment to further control for possible measured sources of selection bias. They all were factors that could not have been affected by training. The list of potential selection factors included personal background factors such as race, gender, education, age, prior military service, rank, and watch assignment. The selection model also included crime and workload measures and community characteristics for the areas where they worked (we knew this from the survey). Interactions between these factors were also explored, in order to enhance the fit of the selection model. Any influences of dummy variables representing the 22 police districts were included in calculating the propensity score as well. A Wald test and examination of the residuals indicated that a complementary log-log link logistic model pro- vided the best fit to the data. The model fitting was done in R, using GLM. The result was a propensity score reflecting the likelihood that each respondent had attended training because of their personal characteristics and features of where they worked. It summarizes the apparent effects of all of the likely measured correlates of attending training in one control variable. This score was included in the regression analysis presented below, as one of the control factors accounting for measured differences among the officers that potentially were related to their views of procedural justice and participation in training. Measuring procedural justice The district officer survey included questions that were similar to those employed in the training academy questionnaires. Trust was measured by questions about whether citizens could be trusted to do the right thing, if they have good intentions, and (in a reversed item) if it is naïve to trust citizens. Responses to these questions were correlated at average of +.50, and the scale had an Alpha reliability of .75. Voice was measured by responses to the statements “Officers need to show an honest interest in what people have to say, even if it is not going to change anything,” and “Listening and talking to people is a good way to take charge of situations.” Responses to these questions were correlated +.41, and as a combined scale had an Alpha reliability of .58. The importance of treating people with respect was measured by responses to the statements “People should be treated with respect regardless of their respect for the police,” and “People who break the law do not deserve to be treated with respect.” Responses to these questions were correlated +.69, and had a scale reliability of .82. Efforts to demonstrate neutrality were assessed by responses to the statements “It is necessary to give everyone a good reason why they are being stopped, even if it is not required,” and “If people ask why they are being treated like they are, it is necessary to stop and explain.” Responses to these were correlated +.47, and the scale had an Alpha reliability of .64. These positively and negatively worded items were mingled among questions on many other topics, to encourage respondents to pay attention to each. Training police for procedural justice Author's personal copy Results of study 2 The results of the analysis of the long-term impact of training on officers’ views of procedural justice are summarized in Table 3. The unstandardized regression coefficient associated with participation in training is presented at the top of each column. As noted earlier, it could be important to control for measured selection variables using the propensity score, and the effects of this are taken into account in Table 3 as well; the measure is labeled “selection.” In addition, Table 3 controls for a list of factors that potentially were related to support for procedural justice directly, and not just through any influence they may have had on participation in training. The most important of them was race. Regardless of training, African American officers were more supportive of procedural justice principles than were their white peers. Chicago’s procedural justice training appears to have had a relatively enduring impact on three of the four dimensions of procedural justice included in the short- term experiment. The coefficients associated with training in the first row of Table 3 can be compared in magnitude, and the biggest effect of training was on respect. The propensity score used to model the selection process was not significantly related to any dimension of procedural justice. This reflects the fact that there was not a strong correlation between having attended training and having a high propensity score, because there was no strong measured selection process. In addition, African American officers and officers over age 35 were significantly more likely than others to be supportive of the principle of respect they heard about in training. Training also had significant, positive effects on support for neutrality and voice. Compared to white and Hispanic officers, African Americans were also more likely to endorse evidencing neutrality, and the Table 3 Summary of long-term effects findings Trust Voice Respect Neutrality b sigf b sigf b sigf b sigf Training 0.200 (.06) 0.216 (.00)** 0.418 (.00)** 0.212 (.04)* Selection −0.255 (.33) −0.193 (.29) −0.576 (.06) −0.253 (.29) White 0.166 (.26) −0.019 (.86) −0.326 (.06) −0.120 (.39) Black 0.532 (.00)** 0.171 (.14) 0.526 (.01)** 0.582 (.00)** Latino 0.118 (.50) 0.144 (.24) 0.289 (.16) 0.276 (.08) Age35 0.223 (.01)** 0.125 (.15) 0.283 (.04)* 0.136 (.21) College −0.042 (.67) −0.043 (.53) −0.168 (.15) −0.173 (.05)* Female −0.104 (.34) 0.166 (.03)* 0.163 (.21) −0.073 (.46) Intercept 2.396 (.00)** 3.946 (.00)** 3.180 (.00)** 3.631 (.00)** R-squared .04 .03 .08 .07 *p<.05 **p<.01 W.G. Skogan et al. Author's personal copy principle of voice was also endorsed distinctively by female officers. The coeffi- cient associated with having a college degree was negative in every case, but significantly so in only one comparison. However, in the long run, training does not appear to have had an impact on the willingness of Chicago officers to trust the public. The sign associated with the coefficient estimating the impact of training on trust was in a positive direction, but it was not statistically different from zero. Recall that trust was also the dimension of procedural justice that received the lowest level of support in the short-term training study. The trainers reported that trust was a difficult topic for them to address. As one trainer put it, We’ve been taught to trust nobody, to show less emotion. . . .We come to see everything as bullshit – going to another domestic, going to a beat meeting, going to training. We come to see people as assholes. But in reality, there’s a big population we never come in contact with. It’s the rest of the world. In training, trust was discussed around a slide labeled “Us versus Them.” It proclaimed that “94–97 % of the public is law abiding,” and the lecture and discussion revolved around why police too often believe that most members of the community are troublemakers who do not support the police. In this study, however, the influence of training proved least enduring when it came to trust. The analysis examined other hypotheses that were recommended by our col- laborators at the training academy. One common conjecture was that officers with higher-risk assignments might be less interested in extending the civilities of procedural justice to people they encounter. However, neither a two-question measure of perceived job risk from the survey, nor recorded crime or calls-for- service data for the beats and districts in which our respondents worked, influ- enced their views of procedural justice or interacted with the effects of training. We also heard that officers in high-workload areas might not have the time to listen to what people have to say or to explain things to them, perhaps even if they thought it would be a good idea. But to the contrary, three workload questions on the survey and workload statistics from the city’s emergency call center were also unrelated to officers’ views of procedural justice or to any effect of training. A key finding was the importance of the credibility of training. The trainers were concerned about this. A trainer reported, “One of the biggest criticisms [of training] is, ‘This won’t work in my beat. This won’t work in my district.’” On the other hand, trainers reported that many officers found that the class reflected their experience on the street. A trainer told us, “I’ll get a lot of participants coming to me after class and saying, ‘This is great. This reinforces what I do every day. It’s a refresher. It reminds me what I do on the job.’” The survey captured this concern with questions asking trainees “How practical was the training for working officers?” and “How realistic was the training in reflecting the realities of life on the street?” Overall, about 70 % of trained officers were to some extent positive about these aspects of their training experience. A separate statistical analysis (not detailed here) found that the more credible the training was on either rating dimension, the more impact training had on their views. Training police for procedural justice Author's personal copy Limits of the study There were, of course, many limitations to the studies reported here. Both the experiment and the survey assessed only attitudes or opinions. There was no possibility of matching the survey data to the personnel records of participating respondents, so we did not have the ability to track the influence of training on other measures of their on-the-job behavior. This was one of the great contributions of the Wheller et al. (2013) experiment in Greater Manchester. Rosenbaum’s (1987) findings in this regard provide an important reality check. In a randomized study, he found a shift in the attitudes and behavioral intentions expressed by newly trained police officers concerning how to better handle victims. However, an ensuing telephone survey of actual victims whose responses could be linked to the treatment or control status of their responding officer found that this training had no notable impact on measures of victims’ emotional state, fear, feeling of vulnerability, or crime prevention behavior. The evidentiary contributions of training evaluations will be greatly enhanced when linkages like this can be pursued. Because we found little guidance in past research, the measurement process for these studies necessarily had to involve exploratory scaling of officers’ responses. As a result, some scales—which were already constrained by the required brevity of the training academy questionnaire—did not include many items. The reliability measure Cronbach’s Alpha counts the number of items heavily in its calculations, so it was often relatively low. However, all of the items in the scales were substantially correlated and (when there were more than two) single factored, and—as the discussion of example questions for each scale illustrated—responses to them displayed considerable variation between officers. A limitation of the long-term survey study is that it involved only police officers and sergeants with district assignments. Officers serving in other units, including detectives, organized crime, the narcotics bureau, the traffic division, and other branches of the department were trained at the police academy, but they were not included in the follow-up survey. However, the Bureau of Patrol includes about 82 % of all department personnel, and those currently serving in other units all once served in patrol as well. As a result, findings based on patrol officers could be reflective of Chicago policing in general. Another limitation of the long-term survey project is that—in contrast to the quasi- experimental training study—it used propensity scores and other control variables to adjust for measured differences between trained and untrained district officers. How- ever, the study had the significant advantage of using as a control group not-yet-trained officers serving in the same areas and jobs as those who had already passed through training. As a result, there were no strong measured selection-related differences among them. This, along with the general consistency of the long-term findings with the results of the short-term experiment, increases our confidence in the regression analyses. Nonetheless, there could remain unmeasured differences between trained and not-yet- trained officers that were not accounted for by the selection model. Discussion The first study reported here found that, in the short-term, training increased officer support for all of the procedural justice dimensions included in the experiment. These W.G. Skogan et al. Author's personal copy were voice, respect, neutrality and trust. By our measures, training “moved the needle” among officers, and many held different views when they left the building. The second study explored whether these effects persisted once officers returned to their duties. In a follow-up survey we found that post-training, officers who reported participating were more supportive of three of these dimensions, but were not statistically more likely to endorse the principle of trust. However, training is certainly not the only strategy for redirecting police behavior. Even staff members of the training academy were not sanguine about relying on one day of training to change the organization. In their view, change would at least require follow-up, reinforcement training. At the time of writing this project was still in development. Evaluations of the effectiveness of such new training regimes are required if policing is to claim to be evidence-based with regard to one of its most fundamental organizational processes. However, in the long term, monitoring, supervision, and discipline also have to be part of the behavior change mix. Call centers and help desks listen in on their call takers’ encounters with customers; foremen pace the assembly line; university students complete course-and-teacher evaluation forms. The difficulty is that everything about policing makes officers’ actions on the street hard to penetrate, and police organizations have always struggled to maintain control of their field force. To fill this lacuna, supervisors need to do their jobs: allocating the workload correctly, staying alert for problems, and managing the needs of both employees and the organization. It is probable that supervi- sors need procedural justice training as much as anyone in the organization, but with an eye toward exercising its principles internally rather than externally. Supervisors and their managers set the tone of the work environment, and studies of the effectiveness of training suggest that it is in combination with effective management that training works best. Likewise, randomized experiments in responding to domestic violence demonstrated that careful training and monitoring can control how officers handle cases. In this multi-site project, officers successfully alternated between arrest, counseling and other strategies in handling domestic violence, following assignment rules given to them by researchers (Garner et al. 1995). Research by Mastrofski and Richard Ritti (1996) touching on the effectiveness of training officers to make drunk driving arrests concluded that it depended upon the organizational environment. The training worked better in agencies that mon- itored the arrest practices of their officers and had policies and practices in place that supported and rewarded focusing on DUI cases. In organizations that were not aligned in support of what they said they wanted their officers to do, the amount of training officers received had no influence on their behavior. In Chicago, one mechanism for aligning leadership in the districts with the priorities of top management is CompStat. At CompStat sessions, various administrative statis- tics flash on giant LCD screens as unit commanders are questioned about the short- comings they reveal. There has been discussion about incorporating evidence of the units’ performance in delivering procedurally just service, but to date it has proven difficult to figure out how to do this in any practical way. A central problem with CompStat is the “measuring what matters” issue. There are valued things that we want police to do that are not reflected in the data flow that drives CompStat, and building legitimacy in the community is high on that list. Holding officers to account for the procedural justice they do or do not deliver, and rewarding good service, could be the ultimate key to moving an agency in that direction, but—in Chicago, at least—it is unclear how this could happen. Training police for procedural justice Author's personal copy Acknowledgments This research was supported in part by the John D. and Catherine T. MacArthur Foundation and the Joyce Foundation. The opinions expressed are those of the authors and do not represent the views of Northwestern University or the supporting foundations. Many thanks for the support of the staff of the Chicago Police Education and Training Academy, especially Lt. Bruce Lipman and Sgt. Mark Sedevic. Readers wishing to review the training materials described here should directly contact the Commander of the Chicago Police Training Division, 1300 W Jackson Blvd, Chicago, IL 60607, telephone +1.312.746.8310. References Bradford, B. (2011). Voice, neutrality and respect: use of victim support services, procedural fairness and confidence in the criminal justice system. Criminology & Criminal Justice, 11, 345–366. Cohen, J. (1988). Statistical power analysis for the behavioral sciences (2nd ed.). Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum. Garner, J., Fagan, J., & Maxwell, C. D. (1995). Published findings from the NIJ spouse assault replication program: a critical review. Journal of Quantitative Criminology, 8, 1–29. Haarr, R. N. (2001). The making of a community policing officer: the impact of basic training and occupational socialization on police recruits. Police Quarterly, 4, 402–433. Hinds, L., & Murphy, K. (2007). Public satisfaction with police: using procedural justice to improve police legitimacy. The Australian and New Zealand Journal of Criminology, 40, 27–42. Jackson, J., Bradford, B., Stanko, B., & Hohl, K. (2013). Just authority: Trust in the police in England and Wales. London: Routledge. Lipsey, M. W. (1990). Design sensitivity: Statistical power for experimental research. Newbury Park: Sage. Mastrofski, S. D., & Richard Ritti, R. (1996). Police training and the effects of organization on drunk driving enforcement. Justice Quarterly, 13, 291–320. Mazerolle, L., Bennett, S., Davis, J., Sargeant, E., & Manning, M. (2013a). Procedural justice and police legitimacy: a systematic review of the research evidence. Journal of Experimental Criminology, 9, 245–274. Mazerolle, L., Antrobus, E., Bennett, S., & Tyler, T. R. (2013b). Shaping citizen perceptions of police legitimacy: a randomized field trial of procedural justice. Criminology, 51, 33–63. Murphy, K., Hinds, L., & Fleming, J. (2008). Encouraging public cooperation and support for police. Policing & Society, 18, 136–155. Rosenbaum, D. P. (1987). Coping with victimization: the effects of police intervention on victims’ psycho- logical readjustment. Crime & Delinquency, 33, 502–519. Skogan, W. G., & Frydl, K. (2004). Fairness and effectiveness in policing: The evidence. Washington, DC: National Academies Press. Tyler, T. R., & Jackson, J. (2013). Future challenges in the study of legitimacy and criminal justice. In J. Tankebe & A. Liebling (Eds.), Legitimacy and criminal justice: An international exploration (pp. 83– 102). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Tyler, T. R., Callahan, P. E., & Frost, J. (2007). Armed, and dangerous (?): motivating rule adherence among agents of social control. Law & Society Review, 41, 457–492. Wheller, L., & Morris, J. (2010). Evidence reviews: What works in training, behaviour change and implementing guidance. London: National Police Improvement Agency. Wheller, L., Quinton, P., Fildes, A., & Mills, A. (2013). The greater Manchester police procedural justice training experiment: Technical report. London: The College of Policing. Wesley G. Skogan is a Professor of Political Science and the Institute for Policy Research, Northwestern University. His research focuses on the relationship between police and the community. Maarten Van Craen is postdoctoral researcher at the Leuven Institute of Criminology (Universityof Leuven). His research is supported by the Research Foundation - Flanders (FWO). Van Craen’s research interests include citizens-police relationships and work relationships within police organizations. He published articles in international journals on majority and minority group members’ attitudes toward the police. Currently, he is involved in a comparative research on police attitudes and behavior. Cari Hennessy Postdoctoral Research Associate at the Institute for Policy Research, whereshe studies Chicago’s community policing program. She received her PhD in Political Science from Northwestern University in 2013. W.G. Skogan et al. Author's personal copy Training police for procedural justice Abstract Abstract Abstract Abstract Abstract Background on police training Chicago’s training program The training modules The short-term effects of training Measuring procedural justice Results of study 1 The longer-term effects of training The survey Assessing the impact of training Measuring procedural justice Results of study 2 Limits of the study Discussion References work_2sqzzsz7p5h77deewrccjotdj4 ---- Surv. Perspect. Integr. Environ. Soc., 1, 39–49, 2008 www.surv-perspect-integr-environ-soc.net/1/39/2008/ © Author(s) 2008. This work is distributed under the Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 License. S u rveys Theories of intergenerational justice: a synopsis A. Gosseries Permanent Research Fellow, Fund for Scientific Research (FRS-FNRS), Chaire Hoover d’éthique économique et sociale, 3, Place Montesquieu – 1348 Louvain-la-Neuve, Belgium Received: 7 March 2008 – Revised: / – Accepted: 20 April 2008 – Published: 15 May 2008 Abstract. In this paper, the author offers a synoptic view of different theories of intergenerational justice, along two dimensions (savings/dissavings) and three modalities (prohibition, authorisation, obligation). After presenting successively the indirect reciprocity, the mutual advantage, the utilitarian and the Lockean ap- proaches, special attention is given to the egalitarian theory of intergenerational justice. Two key differences between the egalitarian view on intergenerational justice and the sufficientarian interpretation of sustainability are highlighted. Keywords. generations, sustainable development, just savings, indirect reciprocity, lockean proviso, Brundt- land, Rawls, justice “(. . . ) comme si l’homme n’était jamais seul, comme s’il avait reçu en partage une matière et une force, offrande qu’il devait à son tour transmettre par l’entremise d’un être ou d’un acte . . . ” (Márai, 1993:164)1 1 Introduction We have been facing threats to our environment and the risk of depletion of natural resources for a very long time. To such an extent, that they even appear to be determining factors in the decline of certain civilisations. One of the explanations given for the collapse of the Easter Island civilisation is re- sources overexploitation (See e.g. Ponting, 1993; Diamond, 2005). Lead poisoning, which is very ancient, is said to have contributed to the fall of Rome (Gilfillan, 1965; Lessler, 1988; Bränvall et al., 2001). Despite technological progress, we remain highly dependent on our environment as well as on natural resources. The scale and the nature of these issues have admittedly evolved over time. Yet, our philosophical theories on justice fall astonishingly short of expectations in attempting to deal with the normative issues raised by en- vironmental and resource depletion problems. Emphasis on Correspondence to: A. P. Gosseries (axel.gosseries@uclouvain.be) 1“as though man were never alone, as though he had inher- ited substance and strength, a gift which he must in turn hand on, through a being or an action’’. the long term, the concept of pollution and the issue of exter- nalities are potent challenges to our attempts at articulating equitable rules for individual behaviour and social organisa- tion. Simultaneously, new concepts are constantly emerging from political and scientific debate, such as “sustainable de- velopment”, “ecological debt”, “degrowth” and “ecological footprint” (See e.g. Maréchal and Quenault, 2005 on the for- mer). They represent as many invitations to revisit de novo the nature of normative issues at stake. In order to do that, these emerging concepts must be retranslated every time into the specific language of each theory of justice. Otherwise, it would be impossible to link environmental and natural re- sources issues with all the other societal challenges we si- multaneously have to cope with in today’s world. The concept of sustainable development is extraordinar- ily fashionable. There is no doubt that a requirement for intergenerational justice constitutes one of its key compo- nents. In fact, its most popular definition is development that “Meets the needs of the present without compromising the ability of future generations to meet their own needs (WCED, 1987:53). Yet, despite the degree of sophistication in evi- dence elsewhere in theories of justice, discussions on sustain- ability devote too little attention to a thorough examination of what intergenerational justice might actually mean. We must, however, underline that several other normative dimensions should also be considered so as to deal exhaustively with en- vironmental matters. Firstly, issues of international or inter- specific equity are crucial also. But local justice (in the geo- graphical sense) or gender issues cannot be neglected either. Published by Copernicus Publications on behalf of the Institut Veolia Environnement. http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0/ 40 A. Gosseries: Theories of intergenerational justice: a synopsis For some of the environmental challenges, these dimensions are even more significant in practice or conceptually more challenging than the intergenerational dimension in isolation. Furthermore, as we are focusing on the notion of sustain- ability, it is essential to differentiate two issues: “Should “it” endure, and if so, why?” and “Since it probably will endure, how should we go about making sure to do so equitably?”. We can reply to the latter question while sticking to an ag- nostic stance on the former question. This in no way means that we are denying the importance of considering the very possibility that we might all decide to cease having children, and to think about its meaning. This hypothetical situation raises several issues. For example, the very fact that human reproduction would then cease implies the end – a voluntary end in this case – of the human species. Would the actions leading to such an outcome have to be considered immoral? Hans Jonas’ thoughts are often referred to as being central, although we are not in fact inclined to consider that his char- acterisation of the alleged immorality at stake here is entirely plausible (Gosseries, 2004a:18–22). Furthermore, the hypo- thetical case of generalised refusal to have children also puts us in the situation of a “last man” which invites reflection on the moral status of non-human animals (see e.g. Gosseries, 1998:401–405). We should therefore remain aware of the specific niche of the intergenerational dimension so that we do not attempt to force into the subject problems which would best be analysed from other angles. Furthermore, if we focus on the intergen- eration issue, it is essential to compare the treatment pro- posed for environmental problems with what would be pro- posed for other matters which are just as important for inter- generational equity, such as public debt management, fund- ing of pension schemes or passing on a language. This paper aims to demonstrate that justice between generations can be understood in different ways and that some are more robust than others. It also aims to explain why sustainable devel- opment as defined in the Brundtland report (WCED, 1987) is unable to exclude two major kinds of intergenerational in- justice that we propose to highlight. It is up to readers to consider whether the intuitions relating to justice that they would endorse in the intergenerational context are consistent with the intuitions to which they would be committed with respect to similar problems in a strictly intragenerational set- ting. 2 Tool box In view of the scale of environmental issues, it could be very tempting to postulate at the outset that unprecedented con- ceptual challenges should be associated to them, requiring a complete revision of our general theories on justice. We can- not exclude that this might well be the case. However, we intend to work from the opposite assumption and to begin by using as best we can available conceptual resources before exploring whether anything remains unaccounted for, requir- ing the use of a radically new approach. To use an analogy, before coining new words or inventing a new language, let us see whether an existing language – in this case theories of justice – painstakingly constructed by successive generations of practitioners does not already provide sufficient vocabu- lary to deal with the issues in hand. There are different ways in which a layman can be intro- duced in a reasonably intuitive fashion to intergenerational equity issues. One of them is to refer to rules for the use of common spaces by successive users. Consider the metaphor of the uninhabited mountain hut. We can take a certain num- ber of rules commonly found posted in this kind of refuge and use them as points of departure for general theories. The following could be compared: “Please leave the premises clean”, “. . . as clean as you would have liked to find them on arrival” or “. . . as clean as they were when you arrived”. All of these are starting points for theories of intergenerational equity based on different logics and with a different content. Another possible point of entry consists in envisaging the nature of our intergenerational obligations through the prism of concepts of private law, focusing specifically on the idea of property as well as on specific types of contracts. Con- sider the famous native American saying: “Treat the Earth well: it was not given to you by your parents, it was loaned to you by your children. We do not inherit the Earth from our Ancestors, we borrow it from our children”. It refers to a loan contract, the next generation being the lender and the current one the borrower. This is not the only existing pro- posal. Burke (1909–14:§165) refers in general terms to the idea of a partnership “Between those who are living, those who are dead, and those who are to be born”. The Penn- sylvanian constitution (art. 1, §27) uses the idea of common property. Locke (1690 (2003): First Treatise, §88) refers to an idea of joint possession at the overlap. The Japanese con- stitution (art. 97) uses the notion of an intergenerational trust. Jefferson (1789) claims that “The earth belongs in usufruct to the living”. And Jaurès (1902) even worked out a concept of “everlasting mortgage”. We should not exclude that lessons may be learned from a closer look at the potential and limi- tations of each of these proposals. Note that once such a full conceptual clarification has been made, it will be useful to re-translate such findings in the specific language of general theories of justice. Using the mountain hut metaphor or referring to various kinds of contracts or types of rights in rem are helpful forms of introduction to the subject. Yet, they are only partially il- luminating. The approach we intend to use here will be con- structed a little differently. It will compare different philo- sophical theories of justice along two lines. Firstly, only the size of the basket to be passed on to the next genera- tion will be of concern, not its composition. This basket is filled with the components which make up a capital, in the broadest sense of the word. Such capital is not only physical, but also technological, institutional, environmental, cultural, Surv. Perspect. Integr. Environ. Soc., 1, 39–49, 2008 www.surv-perspect-integr-environ-soc.net/1/39/2008/ A. Gosseries: Theories of intergenerational justice: a synopsis 41 relational, etc. We will therefore propose a table to sum- marise the key-conclusions of each of these theories, based on two concepts: generational savings and dissavings. Sav- ings occur (generationally speaking) when one generation transfers to the next a capital (in the extended meaning of the word) which is greater than the one it inherited from the previous generation. Inversely, there are generational dissav- ings whenever one generation transfers to the next a capital which is smaller than the one it inherited. We will then go on linking these two concepts (savings/dissavings) to three modalities: authorisation, prohibition and obligation. This approach may seem both desperately simplistic and excessively quantitative. And yet, the use of the sav- ings/dissavings concepts – on top of the fact that they refer to a very broad understanding of the word “capital” – first of all seek to highlight how much the various theories of justice, as applied to the intergenerational realm, differ from each other both in terms of rationale and of practical implications. Fur- thermore, we certainly do not deny the importance – and the possibility – of a debating on the contents of the basket to be passed on from one generation to the next. This would require more than just weighing the significance of environ- mental assets and comparing them with other requirements, such as those connected to the transmission of special cul- tures or the preservation of mechanisms of solidarity. Even among the environmental questions themselves, selections are also to be made between, for example, dams generating green energy and endangered species, between preserving ar- eas in their natural condition and human intervention to save certain species that are to be found there, etc. (see Gosseries, 1997). Finally, two further points should be noted. On the one hand, since the present paper is intended to provide a syn- opsis, we will not be proceeding with a detailed examination of more applied issues where intergenerational justice mat- ters, such as defining the level of a global cap on CO2 emis- sions, justifying the preservation of biodiversity, or selecting a funding scheme for the dismantling of our nuclear power stations (see respectively: Gosseries, 2006b, 2004a:241–265, 2008). On the other hand, intergenerational justice also raises the issue of our obligations to past generations. This dimen- sion, which we are also not intending to broach in this paper, is present at several levels, including in some the theories presented below. It is also particularly relevant for specific environmental issues, such as the integration of past CO2 emissions in the definition of the current share of obligations to reduce emissions (see Gosseries, 2004b). That being said, let us now consider the crux of the matter. 3 Indirect reciprocity One theory, discussed in particular by Brian Barry (1989), is the indirect reciprocity theory (see de Shalit, 1995:96–99; Gosseries, 2006a). The general idea of reciprocity presup- poses that in the event people are able to do so, they are under an obligation to return to others what they themselves have received from them. In the case of intergenerational justice, one can assume that the idea of reciprocity is sociologically widely endorsed in the public (see Wade-Benzoni, 2002). In its “descending reciprocity” version, it breaks down into two maxims. The first one seeks to explain why we are obligated to the next generation. In this case, it is because we received something from our parents that we must transmit something “in return” to our children’s generation. The intuitive idea can then be accounted for in certain ways in the language of property or more directly as reciprocation for an effort on the part of our parents. But this differs for example from the idea that if we owe our children anything, it is because in fact we are only borrowing what already belongs to them. It also differs from egalitarian logic as we shall see. Regarding the second maxim, it defines the content of our obligations to the next generation. As a result, we find: Descending reciprocity – Justificatory maxim: The current generation owes something to the next generation because it received something from the previous one. – Substantive maxim: The current generation must pass on to the next a capital at least equivalent to the one it inherited from the previous one. For those who associate justice with reciprocity, indirect reciprocity is quite a potent idea. It has the advantage of jus- tifying obligations to people who so far have never given us anything and who may be giving us less in the future than what we will have given them. In the case of direct reci- procity, it is the original benefactor who ends up getting back what he put in, whereas with indirect reciprocity, there is a third party who benefits (in this case: the next generation) instead of the initial benefactor (in this case: the previous generation), giving rise in this way to a chain of obligations. An obvious objection could be that a simple donation cannot in itself justify a return obligation. However, the nature of the moral difficulty arising out of non-reciprocation in this case can be accounted for through reference to the idea of a free-rider, getting a free ride on the intergenerational rail- way without buying his ticket, and therefore taking advan- tage without any counterpart of the sacrifices made by all the preceding generations. What are the obstacles in the way of the indirect descend- ing reciprocity view? Firstly, if we refuse to dissociate the existence of an obligation to the initial benefactor and that of an obligation to the third party beneficiary, the justifica- tory maxim presupposes the idea that we have obligations to past generations, i.e. to the dead. It is in fact those obli- gations which are the source of our obligations to the next generation. However, for a state to justify its sustainable de- velopment policies by reason of obligations to the dead is a www.surv-perspect-integr-environ-soc.net/1/39/2008/ Surv. Perspect. Integr. Environ. Soc., 1, 39–49, 2008 42 A. Gosseries: Theories of intergenerational justice: a synopsis challenge to the liberal requirement of neutrality on the part of the state towards various metaphysical conceptions and views of the good life. It can be demonstrated that such obli- gations to the dead only make sense if it is postulated that the dead do exist in a sense that is morally relevant. Yet, we do not all subscribe to this postulate, which makes it difficult to see it as metaphysically unproblematic (Gosseries, 2004a: chap. 2). Moreover, the justificatory maxim fails to justify the first – be it hypothetical – generation’s intergenerational obliga- tions, because by definition such a first generation did not receive anything from a previous generation. How could we then explain what the problem would if a first genera- tion were to squander from the outset a considerable part of the capital available to it? For that matter, were we to view each generation as a first generation insofar as the goods it invented or discovered are concerned, it would become im- mediately apparent that the present difficulty is necessarily devoid of practical implications. A few other points could be mentioned – such as the diffi- culties encountered by the substantive maxim in case of de- mographic fluctuations. It should also be underlined that de- scending indirect reciprocity is not the only possible form of the idea of reciprocity in the intergenerational realm. For the sake of comprehensiveness, let us also point at the ascending indirect reciprocity idea (relevant for example to explain the logic of pay-as-you-go retirement schemes) as well as at the double reciprocity concept (Cosandey, 2003) which involves direct reciprocity transfers between generations. However, these two alternative forms of intergenerational reciprocity are not directly relevant to the environmental field which con- stitutes our focus point here (Gosseries, 2006a). In any event what really matters in this context, is to em- phasise the need to check whether indirect reciprocity really reflects our intuitions about justice, both intergenerationally and as a component of a general theory of justice. The sim- plest method for such a purpose consists in testing the idea of reciprocity in an intragenerational context. Take for example the case of a person with multiple congenital disabilities. Let us accept the idea that she will give us less in return for what we as a society gave to her – which is not meant to deny the benefits we may of course derive from her company. Given such an example, the limitations of the idea of reciprocity are clear. As regards justification, is it because that person (or someone else) gave (or will give) us something that we feel obliged to care for this dependent person – as a matter of justice? The reply is probably negative for many of us. And on the substantive side, should I measure the dimension of what I owe this disabled person on the basis of what he or she gives me in return? Here again, the answer will be in the negative for many of us. This suggests that for many of us, over and beyond internal consistency difficulties, the idea of reciprocity is not fully capable of reflecting intuitions of justice in general and in the intergenerational context in particular. 4 Mutual advantage The idea of mutual advantage is not very distant from that of reciprocity. Yet, it is not identical, both in logic (what jus- tifies the existence of obligations) and by its demands (for instance, the idea of guaranteeing the promised transfers be- tween actors in a cooperative game). Briefly, a theory of justice based on the idea of mutual advantage has to show that a “rational” agent – i.e. one acting exclusively out of self-interest – will serve his best interest by engaging in a cooperative venture and submitting to certain social rules ac- cordingly. The point therefore is to demonstrate that it is ra- tional – in a narrow sense – to be fair and that rules of justice must be justified by reason of rationality – in this same nar- row sense. In practice, this requires the demonstration that gains may result from cooperation between individuals and that these gains can make every one of us net beneficiaries of such cooperation. In an intergenerational context, we therefore need to check how the idea of cooperation can be transposed. A key diffi- culty in this respect is related to the issue of intergenerational overlap (Gauthier, 1986: chap. IX–6). The fact that not all generations are – not even temporarily – contemporary is a challenge on two counts. Firstly, does this not threaten the very possibility of the benefits of cooperation being mutual? Because if benefits are real but are only in favour of certain generations, so that others are net contributors, a theory of mutual advantage would be incapable of justifying that all generations should submit to a common rule of justice. Re- plying to this question amounts to asking to what extent the possibility of descending benefits (from one generation to the next) and ascending benefits (from one generation to the pre- vious one) depends on these generations overlapping with one another. Furthermore, not only must it be possible for benefits to be mutual, but there must also be a guarantee that the conditions exist for the rule of cooperation to be effec- tively respected by each generation. In this case again, the non-contemporary nature of many generations in respect of each other challenges the possibility of enforcing respect of a given rule of intergenerational transfer. The degree to which a threat of ascending or descending sanctions can remain credible in the absence of intergenerational overlap therefore remains to be ascertained. This twofold challenge is compounded by a further ques- tion: supposing it is possible to construct an intergenerational model in such a way as to successfully address this challenge, there will still be a need to verify what that implies in re- lation to our question on savings and dissavings. It would be perfectly possible to imagine that it is rational for each generation to submit to a rule, which would nevertheless be compatible with a gradual deterioration of the stock of re- sources transferred by each generation to the next. There is an ongoing debate on this point (Heath, 1997; Arrhenius, 1999), but it has not reached a point where clear conclusions can be drawn (see Gauthier, 1986:302–305). It is however Surv. Perspect. Integr. Environ. Soc., 1, 39–49, 2008 www.surv-perspect-integr-environ-soc.net/1/39/2008/ A. Gosseries: Theories of intergenerational justice: a synopsis 43 obvious that any serious attempt at articulating a theory of justice from the angle of mutual advantage cannot elude an in-depth examination of such difficulties. 5 Utilitarianism Let us now explore a very different theory: utilitarianism. It is characterised not only by its preoccupation with people’s welfare (utilitas in Latin) but more particularly with the idea that a fair organisation of society is one which maximises the aggregate welfare of its members (See e.g. Smart and Williams, 1973). This is why we can refer to it as an ag- gregative theory. There are several unsound reasons for crit- icising utilitarianism. Yet, it is entirely true that this theory of justice is not primarily concerned with the distribution of welfare among the members of society. What matters is the size of the welfare pie from which society as a whole will benefit, not the relative size of the pieces of that pie each member will be receiving. Hence, sacrificing entirely the well-being of a few people (to the point for example where they are reduced to slavery) making it possible to maximise society’s well-being as a whole (by the fact that a large por- tion of society would benefit from the slavery imposed on a tiny minority), could be the policy advocated by utilitarians in specific circumstances. Therefore, more than any other theory of justice, this one is likely to lead to sacrificial con- sequences, although in its more elaborate versions, it does try as best it can to avoid such counterintuitive outcomes. In an intergenerational context, there is one fact that plays a crucial role in this respect. Giving up the consumption of part of our capital today may enable us – provided it is wisely invested – to consume much more of that capital at some more or less distant future time. Consider a bag of seeds, part of which could be either consumed immediately or sown so as to multiply its volume. If you are a utilitar- ian, savings (in generational terms) are not just authorised; they are required since the goal is to maximise the size of the intergenerational welfare pie. This means that the first gener- ations in history have to tighten their belts and invest for the benefit of future generations. A point worthy of mention is that the idea of productive investment, which is central to this theory, is not necessarily linked to the number of generations following us – at least for investments whose return does not depend solely on human activity, but rather to the fact that they will be arriving after us. This result leading, in a way, to sacrificing the earlier gen- erations is magnified by two extra – and independent – fac- tors. On the one hand, it is realistic to postulate some in- tergenerational altruism due partly to the fact that the succes- sion of generations is also linked to biological parent-to-child relations which inevitably generate a certain degree of altru- ism. It is also plausible to postulate that this altruism is asym- metric, being stronger from parent to child than from child to parent. If such a descending altruism is taken into account, an extra degree – and in this case a purely voluntary one – of saving may be added to the obligation to save referred to above. In other words, descending altruism could further in- tensify the generational savings trend already present in the utilitarian model. Nevertheless, it does not necessarily lead to an additional welfare differential if the actors themselves derive well-being from these altruistic acts. On the other hand, the utilitarian conclusion becomes more worrying if it is accepted that the number of coming generations is, if not infinite, at least indefinite. For one way of interpreting util- itarianism consists in forcing us into everlasting sacrifices, since there is no way of knowing where they should stop. Such a sacrifice would ultimately be to no one’s benefit, since every generation would be obliged to save given the perma- nent uncertainty as to how many generations would follow. Utilitarians are well aware of this problem. Let us there- fore emphasise two factors pointing in the opposite direc- tion. Firstly, a factor which could attenuate the scope of the obligation to save is diminishing marginal utility, a (fairly plausible) postulate traditionally referred to as a justification for aggregativists’ concern for the distribution of levels of well-being (see Gauthier, 1986:305). The underlying idea is that the more a person has of a given good (e.g. apples), the less an additional good will bring her additional utility. This means that if we have an extra apple, it should be given to the one who has less apples if we aim at maximizing the additional welfare generated by this apple. But more impor- tantly, there is another idea, the one of a social discount rate. This has been the subject of extensive philosophical debate for decades (see e.g. Cowen and Parfit, 1992; Birnbacher, 2003). And one recent instance is to be found in the dis- cussions surrounding the Stern report on the economics of climate change (Stern, 2007). The idea is simple: if the rate is positive, a unit of future welfare will be granted less value than the same welfare unit produced today. A discount rate of this kind can meet certain concerns besides addressing the single “sacrificial” issue mentioned above. For example, it would be possible to give a lower discounted value to a fu- ture welfare unit because of the uncertainty as to its actual future existence. However, when it is simply a question of a pure time preference for the present, it becomes morally problematic once applied to relations between different indi- viduals (rather than to merely planning the welfare profile within one’s own existence). In fact, the idea can be put forward that at that level it is still only an attempt - an ad hoc (Rawls, 1999:262) and rather ineffective one – to reduce the size of a problem – i.e. an inclination toward sacrificing earlier generations – which is in fact the logical outcome of utilitarianism. Even if descending altruism is left aside, the conjunction of recognising the productive nature of capital (whenever properly invested) and the indefinite nature of the number of future generations is such that, in the intergenerational context, utilitarianism can lead to particularly sacrificial out- comes, albeit attenuated by the inclusion of diminishing www.surv-perspect-integr-environ-soc.net/1/39/2008/ Surv. Perspect. Integr. Environ. Soc., 1, 39–49, 2008 44 A. Gosseries: Theories of intergenerational justice: a synopsis marginal utility as well as the introduction of a social dis- count rate. The reason why such outcomes seem especially unacceptable to many of us probably has to do with the fact that our conception of justice generally involves a distribu- tive motive besides or instead of an aggregative one. 6 Lockean proviso Before examining the paradigmatic example of a distributive theory of justice – Rawlsian egalitarianism – let us consider yet another family of theories. This time, it is neo-Lockean rather than neo-Hobbesian, and is commonly referred to as libertarianism. Briefly, libertarian views are building on two core features: On the one hand, a definition and a strong protection of self-ownership; on the other, a particular way of broaching the subject of ownership of external resources – in contrast to internal resources which are part of self- ownership. In this way, libertarians aim at guaranteeing, both against state and third party intervention, a strong protection for people’s physical integrity as well as e.g. for the own- ership of their talents. What is of particular interest here, however, is the status of external resources. We need in this respect to determine how to allocate to members of society the property of the goods we have inherited. Consider a first generation allocating the property of arable land. Some libertarians would incline to allocate ownership of such property on the basis of a rule of the “first come, first served” variety, which for that matter is a rule in use in various sectors of society, for instance as regards intellectual property rights. Others would have us subordinate legitimacy of appropriation to complying with so-called “Lockean” pro- visos. In general, the difference between those two major approaches will reflect, coexist with or result in differences in perceptions of the initial patrimonial status of external re- sources. For some, generally right-wing people, arable land initially does not belong to anyone, hence the use of the first come, first served principle. For others, generally more left- wing, the initial status of external resources would be that of collective property, which would explain the need for re- specting a Lockean proviso. One difficulty is that the idea of a Lockean proviso is interpreted in different ways, de- pending on whether Nozick’s views or those of others are adopted (Vallentyne and Steiner, 2000). What did Locke re- ally mean when he said that initial appropriation can be le- gitimate “At least where there is enough and as good left for others” (Locke, 1690: second treatise, §27; Waldron, 1979)? Let us be more direct in our formulation: “At least where there is as much which is left in common for others”. Ap- plied to the intergenerational domain, this could give us for example Arneson’s formulation: “The continued legitimacy of private ownership from the standpoint of self-ownership depends on each successive generation obtaining the equiv- alent of a per capita share of unimproved, undegraded land” (Arneson, 1991:53). A libertarian theory wishing to apply such a Lockean pro- viso will first of all need to determine its content (“as much as what?”) and apply it specifically to the intergenerational con- text (see Elliot, 1986:217ff.; Arneson, 1991:52–53; Steiner, 1994:268–273; Wolf, 1995:791ff.). Let us outline three ver- sions applicable to the intergenerational domain. A first pos- sible interpretation is: each generation should leave to the next at least as much (or the equivalent) of what the first (prehistoric) generation initially appropriated for itself. For those who consider that the basket of goods inherited from the immediately previous generation exceeds far and away the value of what the prehistoric generation would have had access to, this formulation of the proviso may appear too lax. For it would authorise the entire generation to dissave, inas- much as the resources transmitted in fine to the next genera- tion are in no way less substantial, as regards their productive potential, than the resources available to the (first) prehistoric generation. In effect, that formulation could be amended in two ways. The first consists in taking into account the natural mod- ifications of our resources as time goes by. Let us imagine that the generation before us was the first to be victim of a minor ice age which will continue for two generations. Ex hypothesi, this overall has a negative impact (as regards land productivity, biodiversity, etc.). Should the present genera- tion compensate for the difference – originating in natural events – between the value of the prehistoric world and what it has in effect become due to natural circumstances? For a Lockean, there is no particular reason why this should be so. What matters as a reference scenario to implement such a Lockean proviso, is to be able to identify what other people’s situation would have been in my absence – in this case, the situation of any previous generation if it had been the first. The following alternative formulation therefore seems com- mendable: each generation must leave to the next at least as much as what the next generation could have appropriated in the absence of any previous generation, or preferably2, what the coming generation would otherwise have inherited if no previous generation had by its actions brought about a net improvement or a net deterioration. Let us however imagine a hypothetical situation where some of the previous generations – and not this time natural disasters – had damaged, without any compensating techno- logical improvements, the state of external resources com- pared to what they would have been if left to the sole effect of natural causes. Using the above proviso, there would be an obligation to save. Now why should the current genera- tion bear the cost of compensating for deteriorations brought about by the activity of previous generations and for which they are in no way responsible, or at least no more so than the coming generation in whose favour it seeks to meet its obli- gations? Conversely, for those who consider that the cultural capital inherited from our ancestors considerably increases 2I owe this improved formulation to P. Vallentyne. Surv. Perspect. Integr. Environ. Soc., 1, 39–49, 2008 www.surv-perspect-integr-environ-soc.net/1/39/2008/ A. Gosseries: Theories of intergenerational justice: a synopsis 45 the productive potential of natural resources which the next generation would have inherited in the absence of any pre- vious generation, the degree to which such a formulation authorises anew a very significant margin of dissavings be- comes apparent. A further reformulation of the Lockean proviso is however possible: each generation must leave to the next at least as much as what the next generation could have appropriated if the current generation had not contributed by its action to a net improvement or deterioration of what the following gen- eration would otherwise have inherited. This third interpre- tation takes into account not just the natural improvements or deteriorations that have occurred since prehistoric times. It also includes the accumulated product of the physical and intellectual activities of the generations which preceded the current one. The only thing we need to do then is to con- sider what would have been the situation of each generation in terms of external resources (both natural and cultural), not in the absence of all previous generations, but rather in the absence of the single preceding generation. In the language of savings and dissavings, that means that savings are authorised, whereas such a Lockean proviso in no way authorises dissavings, unless the environment which the next generation will inherit has deteriorated compared to what we ourselves inherited, for reasons unrelated to our own activity (i.e. natural events or resulting from the activ- ity of previous generations). This implies, for example, that any climate change resulting from strictly historical emis- sions (i.e. resulting from our ancestors’ activities only, not from ours) and which would lead to a worse climate for the next generation than for our own, would not imply for us any specific obligations – which by the way shows that the ques- tion of historical emissions raises not just transgenerational equity issues (Gosseries, 2004b), but also issues relating to intergenerational equity. While what would be defended in this case by a proponent of indirect reciprocity is not entirely clear, the egalitarian view would clearly differ here from the Lockean one. Be that as it may, we are concentrating here on possible differences between “at least as much as what prehistoric generations had”, “at least as much as what G+1 would have had in the absence of any earlier generations” and “at least as much as G+1 would have inherited in the absence of G only”. And the specificity of the Lockean ap- proach is to focus on the question of knowing to what extent my existence deprives someone else of something he could otherwise have benefited from. 7 Rawlsian egalitarianism Rawls, in his masterpiece “A theory of Justice” (1999:§44), is aware of utilitarianism’s major difficulties in the intergen- erational context. At the same time, he considers that moving away, be it minimally, from the initial condition of prehis- toric men is necessary, not just for reasons of efficiency, but even for reasons of justice. How can both these concerns be accommodated? By defending a “two-stage” model in which a steady state phase follows an accumulation phase. During the accumulation phase, principles are identical to those of utilitarianism (compulsory savings). But this phase is sup- posed to have a limited duration. And the rationale underly- ing the need for such accumulation is totally unrelated with maximising the size of the intergenerational welfare pie. For Rawls, the aim of the accumulation phase is to allow eco- nomic affluence to build up so that at least minimal stabil- ity to just institutions can be ensured. As soon as this point is reached, accumulation ceases to be an obligation and the steady state phase begins. And for that second phase, the principle defended by Rawls is identical to the one defended by the indirect reciprocity view. Like Rawls, we believe that such a “two-stage” approach is necessary. We also believe that he is justified in defending the principle of an obligation to save during the accumulation phase (for a full discussion: Gaspart and Gosseries, 2007). However, this second thesis is not self-evident. What is po- tentially shocking for an egalitarian like Rawls, is to propose for the accumulation phase a principle of compulsory savings that goes against a concern for the worst off. In fact, from this viewpoint it is unfair, strictly speaking, to demand savings from the first generations. Doing so would bring about an in- tergenerational world where the least well off are not as well off as they could possibly be. Merely sticking to a prohibi- tion on dissavings would not have such consequences. Rawls is aware of this problem but still insists on an obligation to save. Let us attempt a brief defence of Rawls’ position the principle applicable to the accumulation phase. His theory is not just egalitarian, it is also liberal but in a very specific sense which must not be confused with its usual meaning in the designation of certain political actors on the European political arena. It is liberal in the sense that pursuing the improvement of the situation of the least well off must be done within the constraints we refer to as “basic liberties”. In other words, defending those few basic liber- ties (physical integrity, freedom of speech, etc.) takes prior- ity over the objective of improving the social and economic condition of the underprivileged. It could then be said that the reason why a violation of the egalitarian objective is al- lowable in the accumulation phase, has to do with the aim of setting up as quickly as possible institutions which could then be able to defend personal basic liberties and that this latter objective takes priority over the former. Now, if we can demonstrate that the richer (in terms of GDP) a democratic State becomes, the more likely are its chances of retaining its democratic character, we are in possession of an empirical argument able to support the claim that setting up equitable institutions requires a certain level of affluence. Although we can agree with the “two-stage” theory and with the principle Rawls defends for the accumulation phase, we believe that an upholder of equality of opportunity should be defending a different principle in the steady state phase. And what prin- ciple should that be? www.surv-perspect-integr-environ-soc.net/1/39/2008/ Surv. Perspect. Integr. Environ. Soc., 1, 39–49, 2008 46 A. Gosseries: Theories of intergenerational justice: a synopsis 8 Egalitarianism revisited We do not believe that Rawls is entirely true to the demands of egalitarianism in the steady state phase. We consider that prohibiting dissavings should go hand in hand with prohibit- ing savings. This may sound absurd. Is it at all unfair for par- ents to voluntarily scrimp and save to provide a better life for their children than the one they could have had themselves? Who could the victims of such allegedly unjust behaviour be? The answer to this question is that the victims would be the least well off members of the generation of such par- ents. Let us consider the situation of a generation anticipat- ing that, at the end of its existence, it might have transferred a surplus to the next generation in comparison with what it had received from the previous generation. The theory we are defending here is that it should not be the next generation taken as a group that should be benefiting from this surplus, but rather the least well off members of the current gener- ation. To transfer a surplus into the future sacrifices to the same extent today’s least well off. It is only if each genera- tion adheres to the principle of prohibiting both savings and dissavings that the intergenerational world that we will build can be seen as one where the least well off, regardless of the generation to which they belong, will be better off than they would have been in any other alternatively organised world. Note that this prohibition on savings has nothing to do with a preference for the members of our own generation. It is derived from a generational impartial concern for improving the situation of the least well off, whichever generation they belong to. Admittedly if this surplus were passed on to the next generation, it could well benefit the least well off mem- bers of that generation. But what we would have to make sure of is that the least well off members of our own genera- tion would not end up then in a worse situation than the one experienced by the least privileged of the next generation. We cannot go into the details here of this rather counter- intuitive principle, or which at least seems to be so at first sight (for a more extensive defence: Gosseries, 2004a: chap. 4; Gaspart and Gosseries, 2007). But we must empha- sise that even if such an approach is not totally incompatible with the idea of growth, it should certainly be contrasted with other ideas in the “anti-growth” family of arguments (see Gosseries, 2004a:224–225, Gaspart and Gosseries, 2007). Among these, let us mention four, all different from the one defended here. The first consists in stating that growth, in so far as it would lead to increased inequalities internation- ally, would be unfair in this respect. The second underlines that the adoption by a State of a policy to encourage eco- nomic growth is contrary to the principle according to which the State should remain neutral as regards people’s varying concepts of what the good life should be (Bonin, 1997). The third states that growth is futile, if not counter-productive, from the point of view of really worthwhile conceptions of the good life. A fourth argument considers that growth, in so far as it mobilises large amounts of physical resources, would not be sustainable at the current rate. Each of these four arguments deserves closer scrutiny, both on their factual assumptions and their normative plausibility. However, it should be stressed that intergenerational egalitarianism as de- veloped here presents an argument which differs from those, notwithstanding the fact that it does refer to a concern for justice as do the first two “anti-growth” arguments outlined above. It is also clear now that the conclusions of an egalitarian theory do not converge, in the steady-state phase, with those of for instance, indirect reciprocity. Furthermore, there is another significant angle from which the proposed conver- gence is absent. This becomes clearly apparent if we con- sider a future natural phenomenon (e.g. an earthquake) nega- tively impacting the fate of the next generation. From an in- tra-generational point of view, a destructive earthquake must give rise to compensation from those who did not suffer its effects, so as to mitigate as much as possible, the negative consequences for the unlucky few of a phenomenon they were not responsible for. For a luck egalitarian, any disad- vantage arising out of circumstances beyond people’s con- trol should give rise to compensation from the rest of so- ciety. A congenital handicap or a particular mother tongue are characteristics which are unquestionably circumstances affecting those concerned. A luck egalitarian would immedi- ately add however that if disadvantages arise out of people’s own choices, their costs should be borne in principle by the very people who made such choices. The debate in France on local mountain communities having to foot the bill for rescue missions to save people practising dangerous sports, or the debate in Austria concerning the non-reimbursement of hospital expenses for alcoholic coma induced by particu- lar drinking habits in the younger population, clearly point in the direction of practices which could well be viewed by an egalitarian as the result of a choice. In such cases, it would not be society’s duty to shoulder the burden of its cost (on choice/circumstance: Dworkin, 2000). How can we transpose this choice/circumstance distinc- tion into the intergenerational field? Let us go back to our previous example. If we were able – by extraordinary means – to predict the occurrence and magnitude of such future earthquakes and if we were able to demonstrate that the next generation will be particularly affected by them although, we, the current generation, would not be affected in the slightest, the current generation would then be under a savings obli- gation so as to ensure that, as a result of these earthquakes, the next generation does not find itself in more unfavourable circumstances than the current one. This obligation to save arises out of a very different logic from one based on utilitar- ianism or the one included in the accumulation phase of the egalitarian theory. But above all, it does not seem for exam- ple, that an indirect reciprocity approach could ever compel us to transfer more to the next generation than what we re- ceived from the previous one. Surv. Perspect. Integr. Environ. Soc., 1, 39–49, 2008 www.surv-perspect-integr-environ-soc.net/1/39/2008/ A. Gosseries: Theories of intergenerational justice: a synopsis 47 Table 1. Synopsis of the various theories of intergenerational justice. Savings Dissavings Indirect reciprocity Authorised Prohibited Utilitarianism Mandatory Prohibited Lockean proviso Authorised Prohibited, unless . . . Rawlsian Egalitarianism Phase 1: Mandatory Phase 2: Authorised Prohibited Egalitarianism revisited Phase 1: Mandatory Phase 2: Prohibited, unless . . . Phase 1: Prohibited Phase 2: Prohibited, unless . . . Brundtland’s Sufficientarism Authorised, unless . . . Authorised, unless . . . 9 Brundtland’s sufficientarianism We are now well prepared to support the assumption that Brundtland’s definition of sustainable development would not be a sufficient safeguard for intergenerational justice. As mentioned above, development is only said to be sustainable if it “Meets the needs of the present without compromising the ability of future generations to meet their own needs” (WCED, 1987:53). Contrast this formulation with Daly’s, according to which “. . . the basic needs of the present should always take precedence over the basic needs of the future but the basic needs of the future should take precedence over the extravagant luxury of the present” (Daly, 1996:36). Brundt- land’s reference to the concept of need can admittedly be un- derstood in its broader or narrower meaning. To our mind, the most appropriate interpretation is that of “basic needs”. But even with a less restrictive version, there is still in such a definition the idea that once everyone’s needs are covered, fairness does not require any further redistribution. As long as everyone’s basic needs are covered, this “sufficientarian- ism” based on the satisfaction of needs would not demand, for example, that a person born with a missing finger due to genetic malformation, should be receiving compensation if that missing finger does not prevent him from satisfying his basic needs (on sufficientarianism: Casal, 2007). In the view of a luck egalitarian, the residual injustice following Brundtland’s sufficientarianism in that case, is twofold. First, it authorises a possibly significant degree of dissavings as long as it is compatible with the capacity of the next generation to provide for its own needs. Second, by au- thorising generational savings – that is as long as it does not compromise the capacity of all the members of the current generation to satisfy their own needs, it is not responding to the egalitarian requirement for prohibiting savings on princi- ple out of concern for the least well off in our own current generation. Let us be quite clear: this is not an internal criticism of Brundtland’s theory. Furthermore, if space permitted, we could certainly try and demonstrate with far greater subtlety the extent to which Brundtland’s report probably opens the way to alternative interpretations. Nevertheless, what is of importance here, is that those who consider that luck egali- tarianism is the most plausible theory of justice when deal- ing with intragenerational allocation issues have no reason to abandon this theory when moving on to intergenerational is- sues. Egalitarians should certainly reject Brundtland’s theory as being insufficient. 10 Conclusion This short paper is based on a set of simplifying assump- tions. We did not, for example, consider the composition of the basket of goods to be transferred to the next genera- tion (e.g. can the oil or the biodiversity that we are squander- ing be replaced by motorways or cultural assets?). We only broached on a very general level the issue of equitable in- tergenerational transmission, on the basis of two categories (savings/dissavings) and three modalities (prohibition, au- thorisation and obligation). Nevertheless, this synopsis has allowed us to highlight two important points. Firstly, using a very simplified framework, one can see in outline some very different operational principles. We can observe for ex- ample that both the utilitarians and the egalitarians (in the accumulation phase and in certain limited assumptions in the steady state phase) include the generational savings obliga- tion in their theories, albeit for very different reasons. We can also see that the dissavings prohibition option is to be taken seriously by egalitarians in the steady state phase. Finally, are also worth noting the departures from the dissavings pro- hibition that are present in the Lockean or sufficientarian ap- proaches. Secondly, it is now obvious that the standard ap- proach to sustainable development as Brundtland views it is by no means the only option. And it is clearly problematic on two counts for an egalitarian. In point of fact, these theories of justice provide resources for thinking not just along different lines, but also for broach- ing the issue of intergenerational justice through the prism of various logics which, if they are understood in depth, can www.surv-perspect-integr-environ-soc.net/1/39/2008/ Surv. Perspect. Integr. Environ. Soc., 1, 39–49, 2008 48 A. Gosseries: Theories of intergenerational justice: a synopsis generate a multiplicity of implications. This is particularly true once the ultra-simplified world represented here is en- riched with a set of additional variables to bring it closer to the real world. Each of these theories can respond differently for example to demographic fluctuations, the case of the in- direct reciprocity view being probably the most emblematic on this count. For certain theories, population changes would modify what we owe to the next generation, whereas for oth- ers, it would in no way alter the magnitude of our intergener- ational obligations. Similarly, the degree to which descend- ing intergenerational altruism turns out to be significant will affect, to a greater or lesser degree, our obligations to the next generation depending on the theory which is adopted. Generational overlap (or its absence) is also more significant in some approaches than in others, particularly in the case of mutual advantage theories. And the fact that a previous generation has, or has not, fulfilled its own obligations (non- compliance issue) will affect, also in varying degrees, the obligations that each of these theories places on the current generation. It is illuminating in this regard to have in mind how a Lockean proviso tackles the disregard, by a generation previous to our own, of its intergenerational obligations; and how an egalitarian theory can take on board the risk of non- compliance with its intergenerational obligations by one of the generations that comes after us. As we can see, taking the standard theories on justice se- riously is fairly enlightening as to the various possible ways of tackling the issue of our intergenerational obligations. To be sure, there is still a long way to go before we can define the precise contours of these obligations... and set up the in- stitutions to enforce them. Acknowledgements. This paper is a revised version of Gosseries (2005). We particularly wish to thank B. Gagnon, M. Fleurbaey and P. Savidan for their comments during the preparation of this paper, the original French version of which is forthcoming in Raison publique (2008). We are also much grateful to Evelyn Apaire Van Gelder for her translation from French. Edited by: G. Maingauy References Arneson, R.: Lockean Self-Ownership: Towards a Demolition, Po- litical Studies, 39(1), 36–54, 1991. Arrhenius, G.: Mutual Advantage Contractarianism and Future Generations, Theoria, 65(1), 25–35, 1999. Barry, B.: Justice as Reciprocity, in: Liberty and Justice, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1989. Birnbacher, D.: Can discounting be justified?, International Journal of Sustainable Development, 6(1), 42–53, 2003. Bonin, P.-Y.: Neutralité libérale et croissance économique, Dia- logue, 36, 683–703, 1997. Bränvall, M.-L., Bindler, R., Emteryd, O., and Renberg, I.: Four thousand years of atmospheric lead pollution in northern Europe: a summary from Swedish lake sediments, J. Paleolimnol., 25, 421–435, 2001. Burke, E.: Reflections on the French Revolution, Cambridge (Mass.): The Harvard Classics, 1909–14. Casal, P.: Why Sufficiency is Not Enough, Ethics, 117(2), 296–326, 2007. Cosandey, D.: La faillite coupable des retraites, Comment nos as- surances vieillesse font chuter la natalité, Paris, L’Harmattan, 2003. Cowen, T. and Parfit, D.: Against the Social Discount Rate, in: Jus- tice between age groups and generations, edited by: Laslett, P., and Fishkin, J., New Haven/London, Yale University Press, 144– 161, 1992. Daly, H.: Beyond Growth, The economics of sustainable develop- ment, Boston, Beacon Press, 1996. De Shalit, A.: Why Posterity Matters. Environmental policies and future generations, London, Routledge, 1995. Diamond, J.: Collapse. How societies choose to fail or survive, Viking Books, 2005. Dworkin, R.: Sovereign Virtue. The Theory and Practice of Equal- ity, Cambridge/London, Harvard University Press, 2000. Elliot, R.: Future Generations, Locke’s Proviso and Libertarian Jus- tice, Journal of Applied Philosophy, 3(2), 217–227, 1986. Gaspart, F. and Gosseries, A.: Are Generational Savings Unjust?, Politics, Philosophy & Economics, 6(2), 193–217, 2007. Gauthier, D.: Morals by agreement, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1986. Gilfillan, S. C.: Lead Poisoning and the Fall of Rome, J. Occup. Med., 7, 53–60, 1965. Gosseries, A.: De la nécessité de distinguer protection de l’environnement, conservation de la nature et conservation de la biodiversité, L’exemple de l’introduction d’une sous-espèce non- européenne d’espèce protégée (note under CJCE, C-202/94), 1997, Revue juridique de l’environnement, 22(2), 220–227, 1997. Gosseries, A.: L’éthique environnementale aujourd’hui, Revue philosophique de Louvain, 96(3), 401–405, 1998. Gosseries, A.: Penser la justice entre les générations, Paris, Aubier- Flammarion, 2004a. Gosseries, A.: Historical Emissions and Free-riding, Ethical Per- spectives, 11(1), 36–60, 2004b. Gosseries, A.: The Egalitarian Case Against Brundtland’s Sustain- ability, GAIA, 14(1), 40–46, 2005. Gosseries, A.: Dette générationnelle et conceptions de la réciprocité, in: Finances publiques et redistribution sociale, edited by: Pellet, R., Paris, Economica, 367–391, 2006a. Gosseries, A.: Egalitarisme cosmopolite et effet de serre, Les séminaires de l’IDDRI (Paris), 14, 18–23, 2006b. Gosseries, A.: Radiological Protection and Intergenerational Jus- tice, in: Ethics and Radiological Protection, edited by: Egger- mont, G. and Feltz, B., Louvain-la-Neuve, Academia-Bruylant, 167–195, 2008. Heath, J.: Intergenerational Cooperation and Distributive Justice, Can. J. Phil., 27(3), 361–376, 1997. Jaurès, J.: Etudes socialistes, Paris, P. Ollendorf, 1902, http:// gallica.bnf.fr/ark:/12148/bpt6k886633, last access: April 2008. Jefferson, Th.: Letter to James Madison (6 sept 1789), Disponible sur: http://odur.let.rug.nl/∼usa/P/tj3/writings/brf/jefl81.htm, last access: 14 May, 2008. Surv. Perspect. Integr. Environ. Soc., 1, 39–49, 2008 www.surv-perspect-integr-environ-soc.net/1/39/2008/ http://gallica.bnf.fr/ark:/12148/bpt6k886633 http://gallica.bnf.fr/ark:/12148/bpt6k886633 http://odur.let.rug.nl/~usa/P/tj3/writings/brf/jefl81.htm A. Gosseries: Theories of intergenerational justice: a synopsis 49 Lessler L.: Lead and Lead Poisoning from Antiquity to Modern Times, Ohio J. Sci, 88(3), 78–84, 1988. Locke, J.: Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concern- ing Toleration, edited by: Shapiro, I., New Haven/Londres, Yale University Press, 1690 (2003). Márai, S.: Les Confessions d’un bourgeois, Paris, Albin Michel (Le Livre de Poche), 1993. Maréchal, J.-P. and Quenault, B. (Eds.): Le développement durable, Une perspective pour le XXIè siècle, Rennes, PUR, 2005. Ponting, Cl.: A Green History Of The World. The Environment and the Collapse of Great Civilizations, New York, Penguin, 1993. Rawls, J.: A Theory of Justice (revised edition), Oxford/New York, Oxford University Press, 1999 (Orig. 1971). Smart, J. J. C. and Williams, B.: Utilitarianism. For and Against, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1973. Steiner, H.: An Essay on Rights, Oxford, Blackwell, 1994. Stern, N.: The Economics of Climate Change: The Stern Review, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, also avail- able at: http://www.hm-treasury.gov.uk/independent reviews/ stern review economics climate change/stern review report. cfm, 2007. Vallentyne, P. and Steiner, H. (Eds.): Left Libertarianism and its Critics: The Contemporary Debate, New York, Palgrave, 2000. Wade-Benzoni, K. A.: A Golden Rule Over Time: Reciprocity in Intergenerational Allocation Decisions, Academy of Manage- ment Journal, 45(5), 1011–1028, 2002. Waldron, J.: Enough And As Good Left For Others, Philosophical Quarterly, 29, 319–328, 1979. WCED (World Commission on the Environment and Develop- ment): Our Common Future, Oxford/New York, Oxford Univer- sity Press, 1987. Wolf, C.: Contemporary Property Rights, Lockean Provisos and the Interests of Future Generations, Ethics, 105(4), 791–818, 1995. www.surv-perspect-integr-environ-soc.net/1/39/2008/ Surv. Perspect. Integr. Environ. Soc., 1, 39–49, 2008 http://www.hm-treasury.gov.uk/independent_reviews/stern_review_economics_climate_change/stern_review_report.cfm http://www.hm-treasury.gov.uk/independent_reviews/stern_review_economics_climate_change/stern_review_report.cfm http://www.hm-treasury.gov.uk/independent_reviews/stern_review_economics_climate_change/stern_review_report.cfm work_2tt76smnojbv3afxsvdcullpou ---- Climate justice and the built environment EDITORIAL Climate justice and the built environment Sonja Klinsky1 and Anna Mavrogianni2 Highlights Climate justice is explained and explored in relation to how decisions about the built environment in the climate context intersect with human wellbeing. Key features in the built environment are identified that impact upon climate injustice. Specific processes, decisions and actions are identified to reduce these injustices and to reduce current gaps both in knowledge and practices. A conceptual and practical context is provided for integrating concerns about climate justice into research and decision-making about the built environment by addressing four underlying questions: 1. What is climate justice and why is it a significant issue? 2. Why is the built environment important in addressing climate injustice, and why is climate justice essential for the built environment community to consider? 3. What processes can be used to reduce inequities and injustices in the built environment? 4. What roles might the academic community, governmental entities, and practitioners in construction, design and real estate, have in facilitating deeper integration of climate justice? A capabilities approach is proposed to systematically uncover and address underlying patterns of injustice. A multi-valent approach involving distributive, procedural and recognition justice can be harnessed to constitute a justice framework. A process of change is needed to: (i) reframe, reposition and extend current built environment research to engage with wider issues of justice, (ii) build and make accessible the evidence base for the identification and mitigation of inequities in climate risk exposures, vulnerabilities, and effective and equitable adaptation pathways and (iii) define responsibilities for different actors. Keywords: adaptation; built environment; cities; climate justice; equity; human development; poverty; resilience; social justice; vulnerability Klinsky, S., & Mavrogianni, A. (2020). Climate justice and the built environment. Buildings and Cities, 1(1), pp. 412–428. DOI: https:// doi.org/10.5334/bc.65 1. Introduction It is widely acknowledged that questions of justice are embedded in every aspect of climate change, and that ongoing and future anthropogenic climate change will exacerbate inequities worldwide. Cumulative global emissions have been dominated by processes of industrialisation from the Global North, leaving limited atmospheric space for similar processes in the Global South if atmospheric concentrations are to be kept below levels that would lead to a 1.5 or 2°C change in global average temperature. Simultaneously, global climate change impacts including sea level rise and increases in the frequency and severity of extreme weather events are also uneven across and within countries (IPCC 2018). Both extreme events and slow onset impacts can harm infrastructure, present significant financial challenges to communities, and generate a myriad of health and wellbeing implications. Such health impacts can include immediate threats to life, changes in long-term conditions including asthma and heat-related stress, challenges to mental health, and shifts in disease vectors (Watts et al. 2019). Climate change will also function as a ‘risk modifier’ in the built environment, exacerbating inequalities and inequities associated with indoor environmental exposures, such as excess indoor temperatures, indoor air pollution, contaminated water, allergens and mould (Vardoulakis et al. 2015). This special issue presents climate justice studies by seven groups of researchers. The papers, which were selected from 36 submitted abstracts, describe work conducted in Australia, Germany, Kenya, Poland, the UK and the US (Table 1). They describe a range of approaches for understanding the manifestations of climate injustice in the context of the built environment and identify specific processes, decisions and actions that can be taken to reduce these injustices. 1 Arizona State University, School of Sustainability, Tempe, AZ, US. ORCID: 0000-0002-9450-1249 2 University College London, Bartlett Faculty of the Built Environment, Institute for Environmental Design and Engineering, London, UK. ORCID: 0000-0002-5104-1238 Corresponding author: Anna Mavrogianni (a.mavrogianni@ucl.ac.uk) https://doi.org/10.5334/bc.65 https://doi.org/10.5334/bc.65 https://orcid.org/0000-0002-9450-1249 https://orcid.org/0000-0002-5104-1238 mailto:a.mavrogianni@ucl.ac.uk Klinsky and Mavrogianni 413 Despite this breadth, the special issue also reveals some gaps both in our knowledge and practices. Accordingly, it aims to initiate a process of change and discussion that will ultimately break disciplinary silos in order to: (1) reframe, reposition and extend current built environment research to engage with wider issues of justice; and (2) build the evidence base for the identification and mitigation of inequities in climate risk exposures, vulnerabilities, and effective and equitable adaptation pathways. This editorial places these papers in context and provides a starting point for more fully integrating concerns about climate justice into research and decision-making about the built environment. It was motivated by considering four underlying questions of direct relevance to those in the built environment community: • What is climate justice and why is it a significant issue? • Why is the built environment important in addressing climate injustice, and why might climate justice be essential for the built environment community to consider? • What processes can be used to reduce inequities and injustices in the built environment? • What roles might the academic community, governmental entities, and practitioners in construction, design and real estate, have in facilitating deeper integration of climate justice into work on the built environment? Building from these underlying questions, this editorial considers the major dimensions of climate justice, and maps some of the ways in which decisions about the built environment in the climate context intersect with human wellbeing. Using a capabilities lens (Sen 1999, 2005) combined with a multivalent approach to justice, it then proposes a framework to help those in the built environment community more systemically locate their work within the scope of considerations about justice in the climate context. The end of this editorial issues key challenges for the academic community, construction and real estate sectors, governments and communities. 2. Dimensions of climate injustice The central claims of climate injustice involve four key interconnected dimensions. The first is that there are vast disparities in causal responsibility for greenhouse gas (GHG) emissions that have cumulative driven climate change. The US alone is responsible for 26% of all cumulative emissions since the industrial revolution, and the EU is similarly responsible for 23%. Meanwhile, despite having much larger populations, India’s total cumulative emissions are only about 3% of the global total, while even China is responsible for only 12% (Gütschow et al. 2016). These disparities become even more stark when considered on a per capita basis. Cumulative emissions are particularly relevant from a built environment perspective because these accumulated emissions result from the creation and use of hospitals and roads, railways, housing, schools, factories, office towers, etc. While emissions themselves are invisible, the benefits they have yielded are distinctly embodied in daily life, have accumulated unevenly, and cannot be ignored in any discussion about the built environment and climate justice. Historical responsibility for climate change has been a central part of Table 1: Articles in this special issue ‘Climate Justice: The Role of the Built Environment’, Buildings and Cities (2020), 1(1); guest editors Anna Mavrogianni and Sonja Klinsky. Authors Title DOI S. Klinsky & A. Mavrogianni Climate justice and the built environment 10.5334/bc.65 M. Baborska-Narozny, M. Szulgowska, M. Mokrecka, A. Chmielewska, N. Fidorow-Kaprawy, E. Stefanowicz, K. Piechurski & M. Laska Climate justice: air quality and transitions from solid fuel heating 10.5334/bc.23 N. Willand, T. Moore, R. Horne & S. Robertson Retrofit poverty: socioeconomic spatial disparities in retrofit subsidies uptake 10.5334/bc.13 C. Schünemann, A. Olfert, D. Schiela, K. Gruhler, & R. Ortlepp Mitigation and adaptation in multifamily housing: overheating and climate justice 10.5334/bc.12 Z. Hamstead, P. Coseo, S. AlKhaled, E. F. Boamah, D. M. Hondula, A. Middel, & N. Rajkovich Thermally resilient communities: creating a socio-technical collaborative response to extreme temperatures 10.5334/bc.15 M. Patrick, G. Grewal, W. Chelagat & G. Shannon Planetary health justice: feminist approaches to building in rural Kenya 10.5334/bc.18 S. Axon & J. Morrissey Just community transitions? Social inequity, vulnerability, and unintended consequences 10.5334/bc.14 U. Passe, M. C. Dorneich, C. Krejci, D. Malekpour, B. Marmur, L. Shenk, J. Stonewall, J. Thompson & Y. Zhou Urban modelling framework for climate resilient energy use decisions in low-resource neighbourhoods 10.5334/bc.17 https://doi.org/10.5334/bc.65 https://doi.org/10.5334/bc.23 https://doi.org/10.5334/bc.13 https://doi.org/10.5334/bc.12 https://doi.org/10.5334/bc.15 https://doi.org/10.5334/bc.18 https://doi.org/10.5334/bc.14 https://doi.org/10.5334/bc.17 Climate justice and the built environment414 all debates about climate justice (Agarwal & Narain 1991; BASIC Expert 2011; LaRovere, Valente de Macedo, & Baumert 2002) and is unavoidable, especially in light of its intersection with other dimensions of climate injustice. The second and third dimensions of climate injustice are inextricably entwined: (1) climate impacts are unevenly distributed as is (2) vulnerability to these impacts due to pre-existing patterns of privilege and marginalisation (Field et al. 2014; Tschakert et al. 2013). Low income, socially and economically marginalised communities, individuals suffering from chronic diseases or social isolation, older and young people, and vulnerable populations will be disproportionately affected by climate change due to their limited ability to adapt (Baker 2012), and these variables operate within domestic and international spheres. Many of those with least resources will face the most intense climate impacts, and insufficient climate action will negatively affect the achievement of the United Nations’ (UN) Sustainable Development Goals (SDG) promoting the wellbeing of people in developing countries and low income and marginalised communities within wealthy countries (UN 2015). For instance, when Hurricane Katrina (2005) hit New Orleans 1200 people died. The highest proportion of victims were people aged 65 and over; African Americans were significantly over-represented amongst the victims across all age categories (Sharkey 2007). Moreover, African Americans were less likely to have returned to New Orleans as they had proportionally experienced more intense housing losses (Fussell, Sastry, & VanLandingham 2010), a permanent migration which represents profound and uneven loss. The depth of inequality from extreme events is intensified even further in countries with fewer resources. A relatively comparable storm with Hurricane Katrina in the Philippines, Typhoon Haiyan (2013), left at least 6300 dead. Six years afterwards, socioeconomic inequalities amongst survivors continued to shape the nature of recovery (Madianou 2015). The asymmetry of inequities in vulnerability between and within societies is a particularly sharp form of injustice. Many of those who are most vulnerable have contributed least to climate change and many of the processes fuelling systemic inequalities are tied to the accumulation of wealth and privilege that resulted in climate change in the first place (Cameron 2012; Haines et al. 2007: 200; Islam & Winkel 2017). Industrialisation and infrastructure development of parts of the world has been supported through exploitation in others. For instance, fossil fuel development in its current form across North America would not be possible without the expropriation of Indigenous territories through settler colonialism (Whyte 2020). The relationships between industrialisation, colonialism, slavery and global capital accumulation (Malm 2013) are not neatly linear but they are deeply entwined. Acknowledging these connections may be essential for designing strategies capable of moving towards more just arrangements at a fundamental level. These interconnections have long been articulated by climate justice activists (CJN! 2004; ICJN 2002) but remain only tentatively recognised in broader scholarship, although this is changing as people come to more deeply interrogate the causes and potential strategies for ameliorating climate injustice (Cameron 2012; Grear 2014; Saad 2017; Whyte 2020). The fourth justice dimension is that temporal, social and spatial distance separates the causes and effects of climate change. Those who have benefited from emissions and those who are most harmed are segregated from each other by social or physical distance and time. This generates new problems for decision-making and accountability. People outside of a given jurisdictional boundary, those inside a boundary but who are not recognised (i.e. those without documentation or citizenship, or those experiencing systemic discrimination), or those who are not yet born may be excluded by decision-making representatives and analysts as they are not held directly accountable to them. The widespread exclusion of those who are most vulnerable within jurisdiction-specific decisions almost by definition presents profound challenges for procedural justice. How should future people or those who reside outside of any particular jurisdictional boundary—neighbourhood, city, country, region—be recognised or represented in decision- making? There is good reason that philosopher Stephen Gardiner has long since identified climate change as a ‘perfect moral storm’ (Gardiner 2006). Actors in any given system have specific rights and responsibilities, and some may hold moral claims against others for failing to uphold their responsibilities. While observations of inequities are important, a focus on justice opens up consideration of both the underlying processes by which inequities are generated and the responsibilities different actors have within this. A climate justice approach can provide an analysis which is actionable based on understanding whose rights and responsibilities are at play in any given situation and how they are related. Examples of this might include not only identifying why particular people are unusually vulnerable to a specific climate impact, but who has specific responsibilities to address these vulnerabilities. Such responsibilities can be based on some causal connection through climate change or some other pre-existing relationship (such as systemic discrimination) or because of roles which come with specific obligations, such as a government’s obligation to provide essential services, or a contractor’s obligation to ensure the long-term safety of a building. In the built environment context, key actors with responsibilities might include individual people or categories of people, such as residents and clients, designers, service providers, contractors and builders, along with decision-makers representing all levels of collective organisations, such as local to national governments, corporations, and civil society organisations. 3. The built environment and climate injustice Due to the pace of climate change and the urgency of efforts to avert it, interrogation of the intersection between justice, the built environment and climate change is a timely arena of enquiry. The built environment is where most people work, live and play; it is literally built into the fabric of society and will be central to both climate mitigation and adaptation to climate impacts. From a mitigation perspective, the built environment is a significant contributor Klinsky and Mavrogianni 415 of GHG emissions globally, which makes it a key sector to include in any mitigation efforts. As of 2016, residential and commercial buildings accounted for 17.5% of GHG emissions globally (WRI 2020). From an adaptation perspective, many climate impacts occur at the level of cities, neighbourhoods or individual buildings, making the built environment a central locus for adaptation planning and decision-making. In both contexts, three key features underpin the inherent relationship between climate injustice and the built environment; (1) long time-frames involved; (2) the embedded accumulation of privilege and disadvantage within the built environment; and (3) the tight synergies between broader health and societal benefits with climate-friendly approaches to the built environment. Each is briefly considered below. 3.1. Long timeframes Decisions about the built environment are particularly important in the climate context due to the longevity and path dependency of the building stock and infrastructure. Built infrastructure lasts for a long time: any decision taken now will continue to shape surrounding decisions for many years—50, 100 or more. The diversity in building stock turnover rates needs to be considered as part of any climate change adaptation or mitigation pathway. Whilst the building stocks of ‘mature’ economies are characterised by slow demolition and replacement rates (Power 2008), those of growing economies (e.g. India, China, Africa) have much shorter building life expectancies and will be building rapidly over the next 10–20 years. By way of illustration, the average building lifespan in China is estimated to be 25–35 years as opposed to 70–175 years across European countries (Marsh 2017; Sandberg et al. 2016; Wang, Zhang, & Wang 2018). In addition, decisions about the types of housing, industrial centres or neighbourhood design result in commitments to particular forms of energy and ways of life that are difficult to shift and, thus, result in a diversity of social, economic, energy, resources, and physical path dependencies. Taking a climate justice approach to questions about the built environment can inform efforts to avoid maladaptive responses to climate change and lock-in measures that will play out for a longer period of time, and to promote decision-making that seeks to move towards a more just society in which all can flourish (Kelman 2020). 3.2. Embedded accumulation The interaction between climate change and pre-existing patterns of cumulative privilege and disadvantage that have been embedded in the built environment raise questions about the extent to which adaptation or mitigation decisions will reduce or increase the inequalities already being experienced across societies. A growing body of literature has been highlighting the urgent need to broaden the focus from the ‘vulnerable’ in society to include critical reflection about systemic inequalities and structural vulnerabilities (Tschakert et al. 2013). This is particularly important for the built environment sector where decision-making processes are multilayered, interconnected and complex. A wide range of different actors is usually involved (national, regional and local governments, clients, designers and contractors, service providers, communities), often with conflicting agendas and priorities. The potential for pre-existing inequities to deepen climate impacts in all countries is increasingly well documented across a wide range of dimensions immediately related to the built environment including heat stress (Byrne et al. 2016); access to public open space and shade coverage (Mitchell & Chakraborty 2015; Kolosna & Spurlock 2019; Smith & Henríquez 2019; Wilson & Chakraborty 2013); and access to essential services (Gibson 2019; Hale 2019), to name a few. 3.3. Wellbeing and built environment synergies The creation of sustainable local communities, low-carbon buildings and active transport are expected to have wider health and social benefits. As stated in the Marmot Review (Marmot et al. 2010), social inequalities in health should be tackled alongside climate change, and these two aims are ‘entirely compatible’. A series of Lancet papers published in 2009 (Friel et al. 2009; Markandya et al. 2009; Smith et al. 2009; Wilkinson et al. 2009; Woodcock et al. 2009) explored the potential for climate change mitigation policies to result in public health improvements, thus strengthening the case for the socioeconomic benefits of climate change mitigation policy (Deng et al. 2017; Gao et al. 2018; Haines et al. 2009; Milner et al. 2020; Vardoulakis et al. 2015). Similarly, public health-focused climate change adaptation strategies at the urban level, such as urban shading, and spaces that encourage physical activity and social connection, have been shown to have appreciable co-benefits, such as improvements in social capital, mental health improvements, reduced obesity and cardiovascular disease (Cheng & Berry 2013). Many have argued that there are important synergies between the previously disconnected targets of climate change driven policies in the built environment sector and energy poverty reduction, and that these should be more strongly linked in both research and policy (Tozer 2020; Ürge-Vorsatz & Tirado Herrero 2012). There is a significant body of evidence demonstrating that, if developed and implemented appropriately, GHG emissions reduction strategies in the building stock have the potential to reduce underlying social and health inequalities, and help eradicate poverty. Energy efficiency improvements in low income housing, such as thermal insulation, has been found to improve indoor thermal conditions, perceived health and sense of wellbeing, and doctor/hospital appointments for respiratory conditions (Howden-Chapman et al. 2007). Although high energy efficiency standards, such as Passivhaus, may be routinely dismissed as non-affordable, recent research has demonstrated the potential to reduce construction costs through multi-objective optimisation, thus increasing their feasibility as a social housing option that could help reduce fuel poverty (Forde et al. 2020). However, it has been emphasised that, for climate change mitigation policies to avoid Climate justice and the built environment416 unintended consequences in relation to existing inequalities, a ‘pro-poor’ approach needs to be adopted (Markkanen & Anger-Kraavi 2019). An example of a programme that has placed systemically marginalised communities at the centre of its planning in order to purposefully reap synergistic benefits from climate action is the Portland Clean Energy and Community Benefits Fund (PCEF). Community led and governed through a social norm of consensus and frontline leadership, this initiative addressed immediate community needs through a broader climate justice lens that included the creation of a consistent and long-term funding source for renewable energy, energy efficiency, green infrastructure and jobs training projects (Mondainé & Lee 2020). Despite these potential synergies, several concerns about injustice stemming from both mitigation and adaption have emerged. For instance, in the mitigation context, although retrofitting is clearly an important element of increasing energy efficiency and alleviating fuel poverty, the potential for retrofit access opportunities and associated benefits are unevenly distributed due to differences in income and wealth or to the landlord–tenant relationship (Camprubí et al. 2016; Gillard, Snell, & Bevan 2017; Schaffrin 2013; Teli et al. 2016). Similarly, winter energy poverty and climate policies may have regressive implications for low income households (Mallaburn & Eyre 2014). As global temperatures increase and overheating risk becomes an increasing concern, several authors have also highlighted the need to identify and quantify summer fuel poverty in temperate climates (Escandón, Suárez, & Sendra 2019; Sánchez-Guevara Sánchez et al. 2017; Tabata & Tsai 2020; Thomson et al. 2019). Vulnerable households are often likely to live in a dwelling prone to overheating located within urban heat islands with poor green and blue infrastructure, and have limited cooling means, e.g. limited ventilation due to outdoor air pollution, noise, unsafe conditions or poor building design (Romero Lankao & Qin 2011). Heat events and air pollution disproportionately affect disadvantaged groups on the basis of income, age, ethnicity and marital status (Willers et al. 2016). The potential for greening efforts—including increasing green space and updating building energy efficiency—to drive gentrification and displacement of low-income households is another theme that has increasingly been recognised within this nexus (Cole et al. 2017; Wolch, Byrne, & Newell 2014). Justice concerns have also emerged from discussion about climate adaptation in the context of the built environment. The most pressing of these has been exclusionary adaptation, e.g. adaptation planning that excludes informal settlements or communities with limited political power (Henrique & Tschakert 2019). Similarly, interest in green infrastructure both as a mitigation and adaption measure has been attended by concerns that the benefits may serve only some populations and, such as gentrification, result in the displacement of vulnerable people (Anguelovski, Irazábal-Zurita, & Connolly 2019; Turan 2018). This special issue recognises the twin potentials that the built environment holds: the built environment can intensify injustices but also potentially address them in the climate context. This editorial combines the capabilities approach with a multivalent focus on justice in order to develop a framework that could be used by researchers, practitioners and decision-makers to identify both potential climate justice concerns that emerge in the context of the built environment and actionable points of intervention that could help move towards more just arrangements. 4. A capabilities approach Identifying systemic justice concerns and finding intervention points can be challenging. An abstract level of claims about justice may miss concrete opportunities for change. But focusing solely on concrete details can also flatten the analysis and fail to uncover underlying patterns. One of the benefits of focusing on the built environment from a climate justice approach is the centrality of this sector to core concerns of human safety, mobility and basic wellbeing. Concern with human flourishing is at the heart of all the dimensions of climate justice identified above. The notion of capabilities provides a useful starting point for making the implications of climate justice claims more visible in actual decision-contexts. The capabilities approach starts with the recognition that human flourishing requires the ability to access and benefit from a range of opportunities and resources. While the exact manifestation of capabilities may vary and has been the subject of some debate (Nussbaum 2011; Sen 1999), a capabilities approach can be useful for identifying how concrete decisions about the built environment in the context of climate change could enhance or threaten human wellbeing. The Human Development Index (HDI) is one rough metric built on this notion and can be helpful at identifying broad trends, but focusing more in-depth on specific capabilities may have some benefits, particularly from the perspective of individuals and decision-makers having to make decisions. Table 2 provides a few examples of how mitigation and adaptation strategies in the context of the built environment interact with commonly cited capabilities. Each strategy contains both opportunities and challenges for justice. For instance, while a positive adaptation strategy might include proactive decisions about how to protect residential areas from extreme events or long-term climate impacts, the failure to do this, or to do this for some and not others, or possibly why some communities are vulnerable in the first place while others are not, raise concerns about injustice. Table 2 makes clear the built environment can enable or inhibit capabilities for people to flourish. If investigated through a justice lens, deeper levels of the challenge are revealed. What capabilities have some secured access to through use of atmospheric space—manifest as things such as access to schools, hospitals, transportation systems, office buildings and safe homes—that have been denied to others? How does differential experience of benefits and burdens occur? Which capabilities, and for whom, are put at risk through particular climate impacts? How do climate Klinsky and Mavrogianni 417 Table 2: Examples of the interactions between climate change mitigation and adaptation strategies in the built environment and human flourishing capabilities. Built environment support for capabilities Climate change mitigation strategies Climate change adaptation strategies Health: ‘A state of complete physical, mental and social wellbeing and not merely the absence of disease or infirmity’ (WHO 1948) The capability of health in the built environment context includes not only the provision of adequate protection from harmful pollutants, thermal extremes, noise and safety hazards, both indoors and outdoors, but also the provision of services that allow people to accomplish their desired tasks safely and efficiently without physical or mental distress, and to promote physical and mental health and wellbeing (IWBI 2016; Perdue, Stone, & Gostin 2003). Recognising the inextricable link between human health and a healthy environment, ensuring people enjoy health, includes all large-scale environmental protections from the regional to the urban to the building scale Outdoor environmental quality at multiple scales (global to neighbourhood): including control of greenhouse gas emissions, all pollutants of air, water and land Minimise environmental costs (proximate and distal) of all infrastructure Protect proximate and distal landscapes and built environment from climate change impacts (e.g. heatwaves, droughts, floods, storms etc.) without intensifying climate change, reduce sources of outdoor air pollution through appropriate policies Indoor environmental quality including air, sound and light quality, physical integrity Ensure low-carbon building does not compromise indoor environmental quality Enhance access to spaces of high indoor environmental quality; ensure efforts to enhance indoor environmental quality do not impose stress on outdoor environmental quality (proximate and distal) Outdoor thermal adequacy Seek to reduce outdoor thermal stress imposed through the built environment, including microclimatic characteristics Protect or enhance mechanisms for low- carbon outdoor thermal comfort Indoor thermal adequacy Recognise potential implications of mitigation policy on indoor thermal adequacy Enhance access to domestic low-carbon thermal comfort control; ensure efforts to enhance indoor thermal comfort do not negatively affect outdoor thermal comfort and/or generate additional greenhouse gas emissions Physical safety: Capability to live, work and participate in public life safely This includes not only the existence but also the affordability of access to physically safe spaces for living, working and public life for all Home Building and operation practices that provide high-quality, low-carbon, affordable housing Minimise vulnerability of permanent and temporary residential areas to extreme climate events and long-term impacts Care settings (e.g. care homes and extra-care homes) Building and operation practices that provide high-quality, low-carbon care provision Minimise vulnerability of care settings to extreme climate events and long-term impacts Work/school/public life Building and operation practices that provide high-quality, low-carbon infrastructure for employment, education and public life Minimise vulnerability of workplaces, schools and public institutions to extreme climate events and long-term impacts Accessibility and mobility Implementing low-carbon, safe and accessible mobility services; reduce non- human-powered mobility needs overall Ensure low-carbon transportation infrastructure, including human-powered mobility systems, is accessible and designed to function through extreme climate events and long-term impacts Cultural vitality: Capability to sustain a thriving cultural life Cultural vitality requires attention to both the experience of individuals and the potential for collective experiences to be nurtured Public spaces Building high-quality, low-carbon public spaces (including protecting adequate green space) designed to nurture public and cultural life Ensure protections and inclusive access for public space in order to meet the diversity of needs this space addresses in the face of extreme climate events and long-term impacts (Contd.) Climate justice and the built environment418 change impacts interact with pre-existing patterns in society that have resulted in disparities of access to material and immaterial resources and opportunities? To what extent is access to some capabilities for some being secured at the cost of access to capabilities for others? Explicit attention to questions about the distribution of capabilities and the means by which they have emerged lays the groundwork for the next big question: what opportunities exist in the context of the built environment for decisions to be made that would be less likely to result in or perpetuate profound disparity in human capabilities? Pursuing climate justice almost certainly requires changing the status quo since many existing systems have fed into or could exacerbate injustices which immediately brings up questions about political power and decision-making processes. For example, in the face of rapid urbanisation, climate change, and already stretched public service sectors, guaranteeing water accessibility for all may require reducing investments in privileged neighbourhoods in order to increase investments in systematically disadvantaged areas. However, this type of decision would be likely to face political pressure from those who have benefitted from the existing structure and who carry significant political power (Baeza et al. 2019). Recognising the political nature of climate justice dilemmas de-normalises unjust arrangements and can reorient scholars, practitioners, decision-makers and community members towards the mechanisms that initiated and that perpetuate systemic injustice. A growing number of scholars have explicitly started to include in-depth attention to the political processes both supporting and inhibiting change towards more just arrangements in the built environment context (Bulkeley, Edwards, & Fuller 2014; Meerow & Newell 2019; Ziervogel et al. 2017). Despite the growing attention to issues of climate justice within the built environment community, this literature is diverse and rarely shares common notions of equity or justice or even defines these terms. As seen in the suite of papers in this special issue, and in the literature broadly, there are many possible ways of integrating justice concerns into the built environment. However, due to the diversity of points of interaction between the built environment and climate change, ongoing discussions about (in)justice in any given domain are not always linked to each other or to broader questions of creating more just social arrangements in an era of climate change. Similarly, even when providing in-depth technical insights, many studies do not link such observations directly to issues of justice, and the majority of studies quantifying climate change impacts on energy use, comfort, health and wellbeing do not provide detailed consideration of the social aspects that magnify risks for health and wellbeing across and within countries (Cheng & Berry 2013; Vardoulakis et al. 2015). It is unsurprising that there remain some disciplinary boundaries between empirical and normative work in this area. However, all major decisions in the built environment in a context of climate change have normative implications. Failing to identify and explore these explicitly misses an opportunity to examine how the built environment has shaped inequities or injustices in the climate context, and how this sector could be used to reduce potential injustices moving forward. This editorial uses the notion of a multivalent approach to justice (described below) as a strategy for connecting many points of evidence about particular inequities to develop a cohesive and more powerful line of argument about how the built environment sector could support efforts towards climate justice. Built environment support for capabilities Climate change mitigation strategies Climate change adaptation strategies Sacred sites and cultural amenities Avoid damaging sacred or culturally significant sites or amenities when developing low-carbon infrastructure; reduce emissions related to sacred sites or cultural activities Develop meaningful strategies for managing the irreversible loss of sacred or culturally significant sites (including landscapes) Essential service infrastructure: Capability to benefit from basic services essential to maintaining personal and social life At a minimum, essential services would ensure all people can enjoy adequate, accessible, and safe water and sanitation (including human and non-human waste systems), food systems and public health Water and sanitation Ensure low-carbon, safe and adequate water and sanitation services Protect and/or redesign water and sanitation services for resilience in the face of extreme climate events and long-term impacts; guarantee the health and safety of water and sanitation workers even in the face of climate impacts Food systems Invest in human and material infrastructure to reduce greenhouse gas emissions of food systems through the entire supply chain Protect and/or redesign food systems infrastructure (including for subsistence production) for resilience in the face of extreme climate events and long-term impacts Public health Ensure adequate low-carbon and accessible public health, including minimising transportation needs Ensure public health infrastructure (and access to it) is protected from extreme climate events or long-term impacts Klinsky and Mavrogianni 419 5. Multivalent justice Any number of justice frameworks have been used to help scholars, practitioners, decision-makers and community members identify and pursue opportunities to move towards more just arrangements in the context of the built environment. For instance, many scholars—including those in this special issue (Baborska-Narozny et al.; Schünemann et al.; Willand et al.)—have done in-depth analyses of the distributive implications of decisions in this context as a way of making visible the often invisible or overlooked disparities experienced by different individuals or groups of individuals. Others have invested energy in asking questions about the types of metrics being used to guide policy making, pointing out that how such metrics are designed may in themselves present justice concerns (Axon et al.). Another strategy has been to look at decision-making processes as a key element of justice in this context, recognising that who is at the table has crucial implications for likely outcomes (Hamstead et al.; Passe et al.; Patrick et al.). All these strategies help us better identify existing injustices and, hopefully, imagine and implement ways of addressing these. This editorial suggests a multivalent approach to justice that includes distributive, procedural and recognition justice (Fraser 2001; Schlosberg 2007) may be a useful way to integrate lines of analysis in the justice arena. A multivalent approach to justice has been used in several climate related contexts (Klinsky 2015; Klinsky & Winkler 2018; Walker 2011) including in relation to energy poverty (Walker & Day 2012). A preliminary framework is presented below which scholars, practitioners and decision-makers could use to identify and address justice concerns within the built environment context: • Distributive justice concerns are the most commonly raised in the climate context and involve any claim based on how benefits and burdens are divided across multiple stakeholders. This includes the division of costs and op- portunities across renters and property owners within a city or claims about the distribution of vulnerability to particular impacts, such as heatwaves. • Procedural justice involves all claims about fair, transparent and inclusive decision-making. As with distributive justice, procedural justice claims are relevant to all climate change decision contexts. For instance, procedural justice could include the integration of undocumented residents in decision-making about adaptation infrastruc- ture or the involvement of communities in national and international negotiations about profound losses (e.g. territory or sacred sites). As already noted in the adaptation context, if processes are not actively designed with vulnerable populations, then exclusive adaptation could result, which reinforces rather than reduces pre-exist- ing inequalities (Meyer et al. 2018). Participatory system dynamics approaches are increasingly adopted in built environment research in recent years to facilitate the mapping of complex interactions between key actors and stakeholders (Eker et al. 2018). • Recognition justice emerges in the seemingly mundane but critically important decisions about policy framing and analysis. It asks how particular people or groups of people are made visible or invisible in a decision context. Who are seen as relevant stakeholders? Which characteristics or specific needs are included in models or frameworks for making climate relevant decisions? For instance, it has been argued that migrant workers and those in the informal sector have been systematically rendered invisible through state policies, which risks exposing them to even greater climate risks (Chu & Michael 2019). Others have pointed out how concepts such as urban sprawl or resilience have included or excluded key considerations during their evolution (Borie et al. 2019; Wilson & Chakraborty 2013). For researchers, recognition justice requires reflection about the operationalisation of concepts and analytic processes. Examples would include decisions about how to include non-monetary losses (such as the loss of culture, health or life); the extent to which data disaggregated by gender, ethnicity or any other potential for marginalisation are collected and used in climate planning; or the time horizon built into any analyses as this dictates who is ‘seen’ as relevant both historically and into the future. A multivalent approach to justice provides a practical framework for identifying potential injustices and linking them to decision-points that could be used to reduce these injustices. Table 3 outlines a simple checklist framework for analysts or practitioners to start integrating climate justice into the design and communication of research in the context of climate change and the built environment. To further demonstrate how the proposed framework could be employed by researchers and practitioners in the built environment field, two worked examples are provided in Table 4. Similarly, although it did not use this framework explicitly, the PCBF is a good example of a recently implemented programme that integrates procedural, recognition and distributive justice aims within a climate justice lens (Mondainé & Lee 2020). This framework allows for a process of moving from observations of inequities to analyses of why these happened and how decision processes could address them. In so doing, it also places responsibility on academics to acknowledge the considerable power that resides in research to frame an issue. Choices about which issues to focus on, which disparities to draw attention to, or which metrics to use are not mere technicalities but determine which and whose harms and benefits will become visible. Scholars can use this framework to systematically connect their work to that of others who may be looking at different manifestations of climate injustice, but that may involve similar causal patterns. Climate justice and the built environment420 Table 3: Framework for built-environment practitioners and researchers to enable the integration of climate justice into decision-making processes. Justice dimension Core questions Distributive Are there differences in the distribution of a particular benefit or burden (including risks)? If so, across what dimensions are these differences manifest (i.e. income, gender, age, race, location, country, time, other social identifiers etc.)? Are these patterns connected to any other patterns of difference in wellbeing or access to resources? Where did these disparities come from? Are there processes by which privilege and disadvantage accumulated? Are some being protected from risks at the expense of intensification of vulnerability for others? Procedural How have decisions been made that influence the distributions being noticed? Who is involved in decision-making, and in what capacities now and over time? Have some actors had stronger voices in this process than others? How did this occur? What would need to be put in place to change the capacity for all actors to have a voice in this process? Recognition What benefits/burdens have been included/excluded in the study or were included/excluded in the decision context being examined? Has analysis included means for observing both processes and outcomes of decision-making? Have the appropriate data been collected to enable meaningful comparison across groups? Which groups of people or aspects of people’s lives are captured by the metrics being used in the decision or study context, and which ones are left out? Are there assumptions built into the metrics being used that systemically privilege and/or devalue particular people or aspects of people’s lives? How does this decision or analysis deal with both past accumulation and future needs? How does this decision or analysis deal with jurisdictional boundaries and the potential for those outside these boundaries to be affected by this decision? Table 4: Examples of integration of the climate justice framework into the building and urban decision-making pro- cesses. Core questions Building-scale example: energy retrofit in housing Urban-scale example: summer outdoor thermal comfort Distributive justice Are there differences in the distribution of a particular benefit or burden? What dimensions are these differences manifest (i.e. income, gender, age, race, location, country, time, other social identifiers etc.)? Have differences in access to retrofitting across any socially relevant indicators in this context been checked for? In addition to the usual factors, retrofit decisions often differ across social housing and private funding schemes Have differences in access to comfortable outdoor spaces across any socially relevant indicators been checked for? Neighbourhood heat vulnerability hotspots may have developed over time so should be examined explicitly Are these patterns connected to any other patterns of difference in wellbeing or access to resources? In a retrofitting context this may including looking at intersections with income and rental/homeownership patterns Common intersections to examine include race, income and health status with geographical proximity to safe green space and safe and affordable mobility to green/public space Where did these disparities come from? Are there processes by which privilege accumulated as well as disadvantage? Are some being protected from risks at the expense of the creation of more vulnerability for others? Common drivers to examine might include rental/home ownership and systemic accumulation of disinvestment in low income or racialised neighbourhoods. Also may need to investigate overlap with social benefit policies generally Important to examine the geographical distribution of housing in relation to green/blue infrastructure investments and open public spaces across different income bands (Contd.) Klinsky and Mavrogianni 421 Core questions Building-scale example: energy retrofit in housing Urban-scale example: summer outdoor thermal comfort Procedural justice How have decisions been made that influence the distributions being noticed? How have funding mechanisms (private or public), rental regulations, building codes, or energy efficiency policies been enacted over time? Have there been lock-in decisions such as fixed grids, redlining or other segregation policies, risk accumulation due to jurisdictional boundaries or jurisdictional priority setting over time? Who is involved in decision-making, and in what capacities now and over time? What actors have been involved with these policies, and what have the mechanisms been for public engagement and representation? What actors have been involved with these policies, and what have the mechanisms been for public engagement and representation? Have some actors had stronger voices in this process than others? How did this occur? Particularly important groups to look at comparatively might include tenants and landlords; disadvantaged versus privileged residents; industry lobby groups versus community organisers Residents of lower income and/or racialised neighbourhoods are often under-represented in planning decisions due to structural/institutional injustice. Examining how such communities have been engaged in all planning processes may be important What would need to be put in place to change the capacity for all actors to have a voice in this process? Occupants need to be afforded a voice in retrofit uptake decisions. This could be achieved through a regulatory framework that empowers tenants (e.g. the UK’s Energy Act, Minimum Energy Efficiency Standards) Bottom-up citizen influence on decision-making could be fostered through participative platforms (e.g. climate citizen assemblies at the borough level). Recognition justice What benefits/burdens have been included/excluded in the study or were included/excluded in the decision context being examined? Has analysis included means for observing both processes and outcomes of decision-making? This might include looking at outcomes such as thermal comfort, household spending patterns or aggregate health outcomes. Examining process might require specific investment in process tracing, document analysis or other means This would include looking at neighbourhood-level thermal comfort; accessibility patterns; and perceived safety and inclusion. Examining process might require specific investment in process tracing, document analysis or other means Have the appropriate data been collected to enable meaningful comparison across groups ? What data exist and what is missing? New data may need to be collected to capture all drivers of potential differences What data exist and what is missing? New data may need to be collected to capture all drivers of potential differences Which groups of people or aspects of people’s lives are captured by the metrics being used in the decision or study context? Which ones are left out? This might include incorporating people’s economic context (costs, budgeting, prioritisation); behaviour and desires for living; household coping mechanisms or opportunity costs, habits and perceptions of energy use into analyses This might include people’s individual vulnerability factors along with social norms, practices, habits and perceptions of urban heat risk, the use of existing public space, and desires for public space Are there assumptions built into the metrics being used that systemically privilege and/or devalue particular people or aspects of people’s lives? For instance, do assumptions about ‘standard’/normative/rational energy use behaviour and retrofit uptake decisions fit this context or do they miss opportunity costs or lived realities of some? Common assumptions about use of public space based only on proportion of green coverage and proximity to one’s home may devalue some people’s use of/desire for green space How does this decision or analysis deal with both past accumulation and future needs? Has the accumulation of privilege/disadvantage been included in this analysis? If so, how has this or could this be done? Has the accumulation of privilege/disadvantage been included in this analysis? If so, how has this or could this be done? How does this decision or analysis deal with jurisdictional boundaries and the potential for those outside these boundaries to be affected by this decision? How have long-term energy and emission patterns and limitations been included in decision-making? How have other resource demands and their implications beyond jurisdictional boundaries been considered? How are broader implications of green space provision factored into climate action plans or other regional visions? If public space is to serve as a water management scheme as well, how are downstream users represented? Climate justice and the built environment422 6. Contributions to knowledge of this special issue With the intent of facilitating greater integration between work on the built environment and climate justice, this special issue brings together a set of studies (Table 1) aiming to frame built environment sector-related aspects of climate change within a climate justice concept framework. Several themes emerge from this body of work. As discussed above, distributive justice in the climate and built environment context may refer to costs (Baborska-Narozny et al.), opportunities (Willand et al.) or climate vulnerability distribution (Axon et al.). Baborska-Narozny et al. quantify the costs of a transition from solid fuel heating to other heating fuel types for disadvantaged households in Wroclaw, Poland. Such policies are mainly driven by combined carbon emissions and air pollution reduction policy targets. Unfortunately, they may lead to the unintended consequence of increasing fuel costs for lower income residents of social housing, where solid fuels are more common, thus further contributing to fuel poverty and magnifying existing inequalities. Similar concerns about the cost implications of energy transitions on low income communities are expressed by Axon et al.; their mixed methods study evaluates the impact of the implementation of a biomass energy system in low income housing near Liverpool, UK. The authors highlight the need to shift the focus from energy efficiency metrics primarily rooted to environmental and economic drivers to a more holistic consideration of just, community inclusive processes that do not amplify underlying inequalities. Willand et al. introduce the concept of retrofit poverty, a household’s opportunities to access retrofit funding, as a distributive justice issue. Opportunities to improve the energy and thermal performance of one’s home are not equally distributed across households. Through the analysis of home energy certificate data for the residential stock of Victoria, Australia, the study found that energy retrofit uptake was lower in areas with higher proportion of renters and lower income households. The authors stress the need to consider the ways in which market-based retrofit subsidies work; whilst they might result in comfort improvements, energy and carbon savings, the fact that these may not be enjoyed equally by all income groups can exacerbate underlying disparities. Schünemann et al. assess the effects of thermal retrofits on winter and summer thermal comfort, and associated energy use and carbon emissions, in typical multifamily housing units in Germany. They emphasise the importance of co-creating climate adaptation solutions with the inhabitants. For instance, particular attention needs to be paid to dwellings that rely on occupant controlled natural ventilation strategies for cooling. If ventilation strategies are not appropriately implemented, residents who have limited adaptive capacity will experience an increasing risk of summer indoor overheating as the climate becomes warmer, which will increase their vulnerability to climate change. Other papers in this special issue explore the nexus of procedural and recognition climate justice in the context of built environment decision-making (Hamstead et al.; Passe et al.; Patrick et al.). Hamstead et al. investigate the socio-technical and governance challenges that urban communities face as a result of extreme heat events. They use actor–network theory as the basis for the development of a decision-making framework for urban planning decisions in Arizona and New York. This framework recognises the justice aspects of climate change adaptation policy actions in order to build urban environments and communities that are well prepared for periods of excess heat. Another decision-making framework that embeds socio-technical information and capabilities for heat resilient urban environments is presented by Passe et al. focusing on disadvantaged neighbourhoods in Iowa. It is envisaged that such human-centred frameworks will facilitate the integration of human behaviour, socio-demographic and urban neighbourhood characteristics in socially just climate adaptation planning. Patrick et al. adopt an ecofeminist approach and uses a case study in rural Kenya to discuss the development of a conceptual and practical framework for the design of integrated solutions that tackle planetary health injustices; building design is presented as a tool that could promote equity, justice, health and climate change adaptation. 7. Current challenges for the built environment Several specific areas for further work emerge from this special issue, relating particularly to how the broader built environment community might contribute to a more just future in the context of climate change. We invite stakeholders involved in this sector to consider how they might fit within these specific challenges and arenas of activity. 7.1. Governance and advocacy • Governing bodies need to clearly establish and formally recognise existing commitments to protect vulnerable people in the context of climate change. There may also be a role for professional associations, education and training insti- tutions, and regulatory authorities to ensure professionals are explicitly aware of their role and responsibilities for guaranteeing human rights and the capabilities of all people even in the context of climate change. This includes obligations for the protection of all human rights, as well as to the non-discriminatory enjoyment of public services, including those provided through disasters and public health emergencies. Existing commitments upon which such obligations could be explicitly connected include the UN Declaration of Human Rights, commitments to the SDGs, and, where relevant, commitments to the UN Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples (UNDRIP). No- tably, particularly in the context of UNDRIP, this includes respecting free, prior and informed consent from relevant Indigenous populations for all infrastructure development on their traditional lands and territories. • Feasible and equitable pathways need to be implemented for the provision of healthy, low-carbon, climate resilient outdoor and indoor environments for vulnerable population groups in a changing climate. This will require the use of evaluation methods for planning and implementation that can capture the range of justice issues, including Klinsky and Mavrogianni 423 those that manifest through inequities in climate risk exposures, vulnerabilities, and adaptive capacity relevant to any project. It will also feature strong participatory efforts to ensure that the needs and concerns of those who are most vulnerable are integrated into decision-making. The multivalent framework presented above (Table 2) could be one such evaluation tool that is designed to be very flexible, although others could also be used depending on the situation. • Authorities need to regulate climate risks that impact beyond their jurisdictional boundary. Built environment activities benefitting those in their own jurisdictions must not impose harm on those beyond their boundaries (e.g. through sup- ply chains or other forms of risk displacement). Working with networks of jurisdictions may be one strategy for this. There may also be a role for professional associations to mandate their members’ actions to account for all climate risks regardless of jurisdictional boundaries. • Governing bodies (including regulatory authorities or professional associations where relevant) need to establish redress processes for vulnerable people. If a failure to meet obligations and responsibilities occurs, then a recourse to seek justice is necessary. 7.2. Documentation and analysis • There is a pressing need to systematically map existing currently fragmented research on climate risk exposures and vulnerabilities by socio-demographic features both across and within countries, and their implications on social inequalities/inequities and human development in the context of ongoing and future climate change. Gathering documentation of inequities is already starting to occur in this sector, which creates a baseline upon which further work could build. There is a clear call for researchers and for governing bodies at all levels to cooperate to conduct quality analyses, which includes generating and providing appropriately disaggregated high-quality data. • In light of the systemic nature of injustice underpinning many inequitable outcomes, there is currently insufficient data and analysis on the systemic barriers to access and implementation challenges of interventions for vulnerable populations. For example, many authors (Cayla, Maizi, & Marchand 2011; Gillard et al. 2017; Schaffrin & Reibling 2015) have pointed out that a deeper understanding of individual needs, behaviour patterns and energy use prac- tices in buildings across different income groups, and their relationship to contextual factors (e.g. welfare regimes, housing systems etc.) is required. This would include research that quantifies the adaptive capacity of different socio-demographic groups (based on age, gender, ethnicity, income, health status, social deprivation index etc.) to lessen the adverse impacts of climate change, and that critically identifies the root causes of these inequalities. • There is also a need for researchers and governing bodies to actively make analyses of risk exposures and of systemic barriers publicly available in order to support meaningful participation in further decision-making. To accelerate the impact of research outcomes, outputs tailored to specific key audiences (policymakers, built environment and public health practitioners, citizens) will need to be co-created through knowledge exchange. Institutions that sup- port and incentivise researchers (including through non-monetary forms of recognition), including universities and funding bodies, also have a role to play in ensuring that such information is made readily available. 7.3. Training and capacity-building • Academic and training programmes charged with training professionals involved in planning, designing and imple- menting built environment projects should ensure all trainees are equipped with awareness of inequities and social injustices generally and particularly in the context of climate change. Further integration of justice concerns into this sector will be hampered without foundational understanding of the core issues across all relevant professions. • The environmental health and wellbeing discourse must further integrate the built environment into assessments of social and health inequities. Health and social assessments, particularly in the context of climate change require interdisciplinary thinking between researchers working in the areas of built environment, health, social justice, industry, policymakers, non-governmental organisations (NGOs) and communities. Such interdisciplinarity work requires conceptual, financial and institutional support. There is a role for all relevant institutions, professional associations, and funders to support such integration. Climate change will inevitably pose a range of pressures on existing systems that already result in inequities. Stakeholders in the built environment sector have significant roles to play in moving towards a more just future to protect the vulnerable and ensure their wellbeing. Although the principles of climate justice may be new to some in the built environment, the scale and urgency of this responsibility is a mainstream issue for our buildings, infrastructure, towns and cities to remain viable, useable and adaptable. The design, operation, maintenance and use of built environment must afford protection to society—both now and in future. In light of current and predicted climate change, it is vital that decisions and actions do not hurt or disadvantage those most vulnerable within a society and those societies that will be negatively impacted, now and in the future. This special issue helps to initiate a discourse about the research, guidance and actions that will be needed. Further research and policy analysis contributions to this journal are welcome. Acknowledgements The authors acknowledge the valuable comments and editorial assistance provided by Richard Lorch. Climate justice and the built environment424 Competing interests The authors have no competing interests. References Agarwal, A., & Narain, S. (1991). Global warming in an unequal world: A case of environmental colonialism. Delhi: Centre for Science and Environment. Anguelovski, I., Irazábal-Zurita, C., & Connolly, J. J. T. (2019). Grabbed urban landscapes: Socio-spatial tensions in green infrastructure planning in Medellín. International Journal of Urban Regional Research, 43, 133–156. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1111/1468-2427.12725 Baeza, A., Bojorquez-Tapia, L. A., Janssen, M. A., & Eakin, H. (2019). Operationalizing the feedback between institutional decision-making, socio-political infrastructure, and environmental risk in urban vulnerability analysis. Journal of Environmental Management, 241, 407–417. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jenvman.2019.03.138 Baker, J. L. (2012). Climate change, disaster risk, and the urban poor, urban development. World Bank. DOI: https://doi. org/10.1596/978-0-8213-8845-7 BASIC Experts. (2011). Equitable access to sustainable development: Contribution to the body of scientific knowledge. BASIC Expert Group. http://gdrights.org/wp-content/uploads/2011/12/EASD-final.pdf Borie, M., Pelling, M., Ziervogel, G., & Hyams, K. (2019). Mapping narratives of urban resilience in the Global South. Global Environmental Change, 54, 203–213. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.gloenvcha.2019.01.001 Bulkeley, H., Edwards, G. A. S., & Fuller, S. (2014). Contesting climate justice in the city: Examining politics and practice in urban climate change experiments. Global Environmental Change, 25, 31–40. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j. gloenvcha.2014.01.009 Byrne, J., Ambrey, C., Portanger, C., Lo, A., Matthews, T., Baker, D., & Davison, A. (2016). Could urban greening mitigate suburban thermal inequity?: The role of residents’ dispositions and household practices. Environmental Research Letters, 11, 095014. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1088/1748-9326/11/9/095014 Cameron, E. S. (2012). Securing Indigenous politics: A critique of the vulnerability and adaptation approach to the human dimensions of climate change in the Canadian Arctic. Global Environmental Change, 22, 103–114. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.gloenvcha.2011.11.004 Camprubí, L., Malmusi, D., Mehdipanah, R., Palència, L., Molnar, A., Muntaner, C., & Borrell, C. (2016). Façade insulation retrofitting policy implementation process and its effects on health equity determinants: A realist review. Energy Policy, 91, 304–314. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.enpol.2016.01.016 Cayla, J.-M., Maizi, N., & Marchand, C. (2011). The role of income in energy consumption behaviour: Evidence from French households data. Energy Policy, Clean Cooking Fuels and Technologies in Developing Economies, 39, 7874–7883. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.enpol.2011.09.036 Cheng, J. J., & Berry, P. (2013). Health co-benefits and risks of public health adaptation strategies to climate change: A review of current literature. International Journal of Public Health, 58, 305–311. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/ s00038-012-0422-5 Chu, E., & Michael, K. (2019). Recognition in urban climate justice: Marginality and exclusion of migrants in Indian cities. Environment and Urbanization, 31, 139–156. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1177/0956247818814449 CJN! (2004). Climate Justice Now! A call for people’s action against climate change. Climate Justice Now! Retrieved from http://climatejustice.blogspot.com/2004_11_23_archive.html Cole, H. V. S., Lamarca, M. G., Connolly, J. J. T., & Anguelovski, I. (2017). Are green cities healthy and equitable? Unpacking the relationship between health, green space and gentrification. Journal of Epidemiology and Community Health, 71, 1118–1121. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1136/jech-2017-209201 Deng, H.-M., Liang, Q.-M., Liu, L.-J., & Anadon, L. D. (2017). Co-benefits of greenhouse gas mitigation: A review and classification by type, mitigation sector, and geography. Environmental Research Letters, 12, 123001. DOI: https:// doi.org/10.1088/1748-9326/aa98d2 Eker, S., Zimmermann, N., Carnohan, S., & Davies, M. (2018). Participatory system dynamics modelling for housing, energy and wellbeing interactions. Building Research & Information, 46, 738–754. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1080/0 9613218.2017.1362919 Escandón, R., Suárez, R., & Sendra, J. J. (2019). Field assessment of thermal comfort conditions and energy performance of social housing: The case of hot summers in the Mediterranean climate. Energy Policy, 128, 377–392. DOI: https:// doi.org/10.1016/j.enpol.2019.01.009 Field, C. B., Barros, V. R., Mach, K. J., Mastrandrea, M. D., van Aalst, M., Adger, W. N., Arent, D. J., Barnett, J., Betts, R., Bilir, T. E., Birkmann, J., Carmin, J., Chadee, D. D., Challinor, A. J., Chatterjee, M., Cramer, W., Davidson, D. J., Estrada, Y. O., Gattuso, J.-P., Hijioka, Y., Hoegh-Guldberg, O., Huang, H.-Q., Insarov, G. E., Jones, R. N., Kovats, R. S., Lankao, P. R., Larsen, J. N., Losada, I. J., Marengo, J. A., McLean, R. F., Mearns, L. O., Mechler, R., Morton, J. F., Niang, I., Oki, T., Olwoch, J. M., Opondo, M., Poloczanska, E. S., Pörtner, H.-O., Redsteer, M. H., Reisinger, A., Revi, A., Schmidt, D. N., Shaw, M. R., Solecki, W., Stone, D. A., Stone, J. M. R., Strzepek, K. M., Suarez, A. G., Tschakert, P., Valentini, R., Vicuña, S., Villamizar, A., Vincent, K. E., Warren, R., White, L. L., Wilbanks, T. J., Wong, P. P., & Yohe, G. W. (2014). Technical summary. In Field, C. B., Barros, V. https://doi.org/10.1111/1468-2427.12725 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jenvman.2019.03.138 https://doi.org/10.1596/978-0-8213-8845-7 https://doi.org/10.1596/978-0-8213-8845-7 http://gdrights.org/wp-content/uploads/2011/12/EASD-final.pdf https://doi.org/10.1016/j.gloenvcha.2019.01.001 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.gloenvcha.2014.01.009 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.gloenvcha.2014.01.009 https://doi.org/10.1088/1748-9326/11/9/095014 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.gloenvcha.2011.11.004 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.enpol.2016.01.016 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.enpol.2011.09.036 https://doi.org/10.1007/s00038-012-0422-5 https://doi.org/10.1007/s00038-012-0422-5 https://doi.org/10.1177/0956247818814449 http://climatejustice.blogspot.com/2004_11_23_archive.html https://doi.org/10.1136/jech-2017-209201 https://doi.org/10.1088/1748-9326/aa98d2 https://doi.org/10.1088/1748-9326/aa98d2 https://doi.org/10.1080/09613218.2017.1362919 https://doi.org/10.1080/09613218.2017.1362919 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.enpol.2019.01.009 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.enpol.2019.01.009 Klinsky and Mavrogianni 425 R., Dokken, D. J., Mach, K. J., Mastrandrea, M. D., Bilir, T. E., Chatterjee, M., Ebi, K. L., Estrada, Y. O., Genova, R. C., Girma, B., Kissel, E. S., Levy, A. N., MacCracken, S., Mastrandrea, P. R., & White, L. L. (Eds.). Climate change 2014: Impacts, adaptation, and vulnerability. Part A: Global and sectoral aspects. Contribution of Working Group II to the Fifth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change. Cambridge University Press. Forde, J., Hopfe, C. J., McLeod, R. S., & Evins, R. (2020). Temporal optimization for affordable and resilient Passivhaus dwellings in the social housing sector. Applied Energy, 261, 114383. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j. apenergy.2019.114383 Fraser, N. (2001). Recognition without ethics? Theory, Culture and Society, 18, 21–42. DOI: https://doi. org/10.1177/02632760122051760 Friel, S., Dangour, A. D., Garnett, T., Lock, K., Chalabi, Z., Roberts, I., Butler, A., Butler, C. D., Waage, J., McMichael, A. J., & Haines, A. (2009). Public health benefits of strategies to reduce greenhouse-gas emissions: Food and agriculture. Lancet, 374, 2016–2025. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(09)61753-0 Fussell, E., Sastry, N., & Van Landingham, M. (2010). Race, socioeconomic status, and return migration to New Orleans after Hurricane Katrina. Population and Environment, 31, 20–42. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11111-009-0092-2 Gao, J., Kovats, S., Vardoulakis, S., Wilkinson, P., Woodward, A., Li, J., Gu, S., Liu, X., Wu, H., Wang, J., Song, X., Zhai, Y., Zhao, J., & Liu, Q. (2018). Public health co-benefits of greenhouse gas emissions reduction: A systematic review. Science of the Total Environment, 627, 388–402. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.scitotenv.2018.01.193 Gardiner, S. (2006). A perfect moral storm. Environmental Values, 15, 397–413. DOI: https://doi. org/10.3197/096327106778226293 Gibson, A. (2019). Climate change for individuals experiencing homelessness: Recommendations for improving policy, research, and services. Environmental Justice, 12, 159–163. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1089/env.2018.0032 Gillard, R., Snell, C., & Bevan, M. (2017). Advancing an energy justice perspective of fuel poverty: Household vulnerability and domestic retrofit policy in the United Kingdom. Energy Research and Social Science, 29, 53–61. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.erss.2017.05.012 Grear, A. (2014). Towards ‘climate justice’? A critical reflection on legal subjectivity and climate injustice: warning signals, patterned hierarchies, directions for future law and policy. Journal of Human Rights and the Environment, 5, 103-133. DOI: https://doi.org/10.4337/jhre.2014.02.08 Gütschow, J., Jeffery, M. L., Gieseke, R., Gebel, R., Stevens, D., Krapp, M., & Rocha, M. (2016). The PRIMAP-hist national historical emissions time series. Earth System Science Data, 8, 571–603. DOI: https://doi.org/10.5194/ essd-8-571-2016 Haines, A., McMichael, A. J., Smith, K. R., Roberts, I., Woodcock, J., Markandya, A., Armstrong, B. G., Campbell-Lendrum, D., Dangour, A. D., Davies, M., Bruce, N., Tonne, C., Barrett, M., & Wilkinson, P. (2009). Public health benefits of strategies to reduce greenhouse-gas emissions: Overview and implications for policy makers. Lancet, 374, 2104–2114. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(09)61759-1 Haines, A., Smith, K. R., Anderson, D., Epstein, P. R., McMichael, A. J., Roberts, I., Wilkinson, P., Woodcock, J., & Woods, J. (2007). Policies for accelerating access to clean energy, improving health, advancing development, and mitigating climate change. Lancet, 370, 1264–1281. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(07)61257-4 Hale, M. R. (2019). Fountains for environmental justice: Public water, homelessness, and migration in the face of global environmental change. Environmental Justice, 12, 33–40. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1089/env.2018.0031 Henrique, K. P., & Tschakert, P. (2019). Contested grounds: Adaptation to flooding and the politics of (in)visibility in São Paulo’s eastern periphery. Geoforum, 104, 181–192. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.geoforum.2019.04.026 Howden-Chapman, P., Matheson, A., Crane, J., Viggers, H., Cunningham, M., Blakely, T., Cunningham, C., Woodward, A., Saville-Smith, K., O’Dea, D., Kennedy, M., Baker, M., Waipara, N., Chapman, R., & Davie, G. (2007). Effect of insulating existing houses on health inequality: Cluster randomised study in the community. British Medical Journal, 334, 460–464. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1136/bmj.39070.573032.80 ICJN. (2002). Bali Principles of Climate Justice. International Climate Justice Network (IJCN). Retrieved from http:// www.indiaresource.org/issues/energycc/2003/baliprinciples.html IPCC. (2018). Global warming of 1.5°C. An IPCC special report on the impacts of global warming of 1.5°C above pre-industrial levels and related global greenhouse gas emission pathways, in the context of strengthening the global response to the threat of climate change, sustainable development, and efforts to eradicate poverty. [Masson-Delmotte, V., P. Zhai, H.-O. Pörtner, D. Roberts, J. Skea, P.R. Shukla, A. Pirani, W. Moufouma-Okia, C. Péan, R. Pidcock, S. Connors, J.B.R. Matthews, Y. Chen, X. Zhou, M.I. Gomis, E. Lonnoy, T. Maycock, M. Tignor, and T. Waterfield (eds)]. Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC). https://www.ipcc.ch/sr15/ Islam, S. N., & Winkel, J. (2017). Climate Change and Social Inequality (Working Paper No. 152 ST/ESA/2017/ DWP/152, October). Department of Economic & Social Affairs (DESA). Retrieved from https://www.un.org/esa/ desa/papers/2017/wp152_2017.pdf IWBI. (2016). The WELL building standard v1 with May 2016 addenda. International WELL Building Institute (IWBI), Delos Living LLC. Kelman, I. (2020). Disaster by choice: How our actions turn natural hazards into catastrophes. Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.apenergy.2019.114383 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.apenergy.2019.114383 https://doi.org/10.1177/02632760122051760 https://doi.org/10.1177/02632760122051760 https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(09)61753-0 https://doi.org/10.1007/s11111-009-0092-2 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.scitotenv.2018.01.193 https://doi.org/10.3197/096327106778226293 https://doi.org/10.3197/096327106778226293 https://doi.org/10.1089/env.2018.0032 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.erss.2017.05.012 https://doi.org/10.4337/jhre.2014.02.08 https://doi.org/10.5194/essd-8-571-2016 https://doi.org/10.5194/essd-8-571-2016 https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(09)61759-1 https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(07)61257-4 https://doi.org/10.1089/env.2018.0031 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.geoforum.2019.04.026 https://doi.org/10.1136/bmj.39070.573032.80 http://www.indiaresource.org/issues/energycc/2003/baliprinciples.html http://www.indiaresource.org/issues/energycc/2003/baliprinciples.html https://www.ipcc.ch/sr15/ https://www.un.org/esa/desa/papers/2017/wp152_2017.pdf https://www.un.org/esa/desa/papers/2017/wp152_2017.pdf Climate justice and the built environment426 Klinsky, S. (2015). Justice and boundary setting in greenhouse gas cap and trade policy: A case study of the western climate initiative. Annals of the Association of American Geographers, 105, 105–122. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1080/ 00045608.2014.960043 Klinsky, S., & Winkler, H. (2018). Building equity in: Strategies for integrating equity into modelling for a 1.5°C world. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society A, 376, 20160461. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1098/rsta.2016.0461 Kolosna, C., & Spurlock, D. (2019). Uniting geospatial assessment of neighborhood urban tree canopy with plan and ordinance evaluation for environmental justice. Urban Forestry and Urban Greening, 40, 215–223. DOI: https://doi. org/10.1016/j.ufug.2018.11.010 LaRovere, E., Valente de Macedo, L., & Baumert, K. (2002). The Brazilian proposal on relative responsibility for global warming. In Baumert, K. A., Blanchard, O., Llosa, S., & Perkaus, J. (Eds.), Building on the Kyoto Protocol: Options for protecting the climate (pp. 157–173). World Resources Institute. Madianou, M. (2015). Digital inequality and second-order disasters: Social media in the Typhoon Haiyan recovery. Social Media Society, 1, 2056305115603386. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1177/2056305115603386 Mallaburn, P. S., & Eyre, N. (2014). Lessons from energy efficiency policy and programmes in the UK from 1973 to 2013. Energy Efficiency, 7, 23–41. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12053-013-9197-7 Malm, A. (2013). The origins of fossil capital: From water to steam in the British cotton industry. Historical Materialism, 21, 15–68. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1163/1569206X-12341279 Markandya, A., Armstrong, B. G., Hales, S., Chiabai, A., Criqui, P., Mima, S., Tonne, C., & Wilkinson, P. (2009). Public health benefits of strategies to reduce greenhouse-gas emissions: low-carbon electricity generation. Lancet, 374, 2006–2015. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(09)61715-3 Markkanen, S., & Anger-Kraavi, A. (2019). Social impacts of climate change mitigation policies and their implications for inequality. Climate Policy, 19, 827–844. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1080/14693062.2019.1596873 Marmot, M., Allen, J., Goldblatt, P., Boyce, T., McNeish, D., Grady, M., & Geddes, I. (2010). Fair society healthy lives: The Marmot Review, strategic review of health inequalities in England post-2010. Institute of Health Equity, University College London (UCL). Marsh, R. (2017). Building lifespan: Effect on the environmental impact of building components in a Danish perspective. Architecture and Engineering Design Management, 13, 80–100. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1080/174520 07.2016.1205471 Meerow, S., & Newell, J. P. (2019). Urban resilience for whom, what, when, where, and why? Urban Geography, 40, 309–329. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1080/02723638.2016.1206395 Meyer, M. A., Hendricks, M., Newman, G. D., Hicks Masterson, J., Cooper, J. T., Sansom, G., Gharaibeh, N., et al. (2018). Participatory action research: Tools for disaster resilience education. International Journal of Disaster Resilience in the Built Environment, 9(4–5), 402–419. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1108/IJDRBE-02-2017-0015 Milner, J., Hamilton, I., Woodcock, J., Williams, M., Davies, M., Wilkinson, P., & Haines, A. (2020). Health benefits of policies to reduce carbon emissions. British Medical Journal, 368. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1136/bmj.l6758 Mitchell, B. C., & Chakraborty, J. (2015). Landscapes of thermal inequity: Disproportionate exposure to urban heat in the three largest US cities. Environmental Research Letters, 10, 115005. DOI: https://doi. org/10.1088/1748-9326/10/11/115005 Mondainé, E. D., & Lee, M. (2020). Commentary: Beyond theory: Climate justice in practice. Buildings & Cities. https:// www.buildingsandcities.org/insights/commentaries/beyond-theory-climate-justice-practice.html Nussbaum, M. C. (2011). Capabilities, entitlements, rights: Supplementation and critique. Journal of Human Development Capabilities, 12, 23–37. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1080/19452829.2011.541731 Perdue, W. C., Stone, L. A., & Gostin, L. O. (2003). The built environment and its relationship to the public’s health: The legal framework. American Journal of Public Health 93, 1390–1394. DOI: https://doi.org/10.2105/ AJPH.93.9.1390 Power, A. (2008). Does demolition or refurbishment of old and inefficient homes help to increase our environmental, social and economic viability? Energy Policy, Foresight Sustainable Energy Management and the Built Environment Project, 36, 4487–4501. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.enpol.2008.09.022 Romero Lankao, P., & Qin, H. (2011). Conceptualizing urban vulnerability to global climate and environmental change. Current Opinions in Environmental Sustainability, 3, 142–149. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cosust.2010.12.016 Saad, A. (2017). Toward a justice framework for understanding and responding to climate migration and displacement. Environmental Justice, 10, 98–101. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1089/env.2016.0033 Sánchez-Guevara Sánchez, C., Mavrogianni, A., & Neila González, F. J. (2017). On the minimal thermal habitability conditions in low income dwellings in Spain for a new definition of fuel poverty. Building and Environment, 114, 344–356. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.buildenv.2016.12.029 Sandberg, N. H., Sartori, I., Heidrich, O., Dawson, R., Dascalaki, E., Dimitriou, S., Vimm-r, T., Filippidou, F., Stegnar, G., Šijanec Zavrl, M., & Brattebø, H. (2016). Dynamic building stock modelling: Application to 11 European countries to support the energy efficiency and retrofit ambitions of the EU. Energy and Buildings, 132, 26–38. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.enbuild.2016.05.100 https://doi.org/10.1080/00045608.2014.960043 https://doi.org/10.1080/00045608.2014.960043 https://doi.org/10.1098/rsta.2016.0461 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ufug.2018.11.010 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ufug.2018.11.010 https://doi.org/10.1177/2056305115603386 https://doi.org/10.1007/s12053-013-9197-7 https://doi.org/10.1163/1569206X-12341279 https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(09)61715-3 https://doi.org/10.1080/14693062.2019.1596873 https://doi.org/10.1080/17452007.2016.1205471 https://doi.org/10.1080/17452007.2016.1205471 https://doi.org/10.1080/02723638.2016.1206395 https://doi.org/10.1108/IJDRBE-02-2017-0015 https://doi.org/10.1136/bmj.l6758 https://doi.org/10.1088/1748-9326/10/11/115005 https://doi.org/10.1088/1748-9326/10/11/115005 https://www.buildingsandcities.org/insights/commentaries/beyond-theory-climate-justice-practice.html https://www.buildingsandcities.org/insights/commentaries/beyond-theory-climate-justice-practice.html https://doi.org/10.1080/19452829.2011.541731 https://doi.org/10.2105/AJPH.93.9.1390 https://doi.org/10.2105/AJPH.93.9.1390 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.enpol.2008.09.022 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.cosust.2010.12.016 https://doi.org/10.1089/env.2016.0033 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.buildenv.2016.12.029 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.enbuild.2016.05.100 Klinsky and Mavrogianni 427 Schaffrin, A. (2013). Who pays for climate mitigation? An empirical investigation on the distributional effects of climate policy in the housing sector. Energy and Buildings, 59, 265–272. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j. enbuild.2012.12.033 Schaffrin, A., & Reibling, N. (2015). Household energy and climate mitigation policies: Investigating energy practices in the housing sector. Energy Policy, 77, 1–10. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.enpol.2014.12.002 Schlosberg, D. (2007). Defining environmental justice: Theories, movements, and nature. Oxford University Press. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199286294.001.0001 Sen, A. (1999). Development as freedom. Oxford University Press. Sen, A. (2005). Human rights and capabilities. Journal of Human Development, 6, 151–166. DOI: https://doi. org/10.1080/14649880500120491 Sharkey, P. (2007). Survival and death in New Orleans: An empirical look at the human impact of Katrina. Journal of Black Studies, 37, 482–501. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1177/0021934706296188 Smith, K. R., Jerrett, M., Anderson, H. R., Burnett, R. T., Stone, V., Derwent, R., Atkinson, R. W., Cohen, A., Shonkoff, S. B., Krewski, D., Pope, C. A., Thun, M. J., & Thurston, G. (2009). Public health benefits of strategies to reduce greenhouse-gas emissions: Health implications of short-lived greenhouse pollutants. Lancet, 374, 2091–2103. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(09)61716-5 Smith, P., & Henríquez, C. (2019). Public spaces as climate justice places? Climate quality in the city of Chillán, Chile. Environmental Justice, 12, 164–174. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1089/env.2018.0041 Tabata, T., & Tsai, P. (2020). Fuel poverty in summer: An empirical analysis using microdata for Japan. Science of the Total Environment, 703, 135038. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.scitotenv.2019.135038 Teli, D., Dimitriou, T., James, P., Bahaj, A., Ellison, L., & Waggott, A. (2016). Fuel poverty-induced ‘prebound effect’ in achieving the anticipated carbon savings from social housing retrofit. Building Services and Engineering Research Technology, 37, 176–193. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1177/0143624415621028 Thomson, H., Simcock, N., Bouzarovski, S., & Petrova, S. (2019). Energy poverty and indoor cooling: An overlooked issue in Europe. Energy and Buildings, 196, 21–29. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.enbuild.2019.05.014 Tozer, L. (2020). Catalyzing political momentum for the effective implementation of decarbonization for urban buildings. Energy Policy, 136, 111042. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.enpol.2019.111042 Tschakert, P., van Oort, B., Clair, A. L. S., & LaMadrid, A. (2013). Inequality and transformation analyses: A complementary lens for addressing vulnerability to climate change. Climate and Development, 5, 340–350. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1080/17565529.2013.828583 Turan, Z. (2018). Finding the ‘local green voice’? Waterfront development, environmental justice, and participatory planning in Gowanus, NY. Urbani Izziv, 29, 79–94. DOI: https://doi.org/10.5379/ urbani-izziv-en-2018-29-supplement-005 UN. (2015). Transforming our world: The 2030 Agenda for Sustainable Development, Resolution adopted by the General Assembly on 25 September 2015. United Nations (UN). DOI: https://doi.org/10.1891/9780826190123.ap02 Ürge-Vorsatz, D., & Tirado Herrero, S. (2012). Building synergies between climate change mitigation and energy poverty alleviation. Energy Policy, 49, 83–90. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.enpol.2011.11.093 Vardoulakis, S., Dimitroulopoulou, C., Thornes, J., Lai, K.-M., Taylor, J., Myers, I., Heaviside, C., Mavrogianni, A., Shrubsole, C., Chalabi, Z., Davies, M., & Wilkinson, P. (2015). Impact of climate change on the domestic indoor environment and associated health risks in the UK. Environment International, 85, 299–313. DOI: https:// doi.org/10.1016/j.envint.2015.09.010 Walker, G. (2011). Environmental justice. Routledge. Walker, G., & Day, R. (2012). Fuel poverty as injustice: Integrating distribution, recognition and procedure in the struggle for affordable warmth. Energy Policy, 49, 69–75. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.enpol.2012.01.044 Wang, J., Zhang, Y., & Wang, Y. (2018). Environmental impacts of short building lifespans in China considering time value. Journal of Cleaner Production, 203, 696–707. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jclepro.2018.08.314 Watts, N., Amann, M., Arnell, N., Ayeb-Karlsson, S., Belesova, K., Boykoff, M., Byass, P., Cai, W., Campbell-Lendrum, D., Capstick, S., Chambers, J., Dalin, C., Daly, M., Dasandi, N., Davies, M., Drummond, P., Dubrow, R., Ebi, K. L., Eckelman, M., Ekins, P., Escobar, L. E., Fernandez Montoya, L., Georgeson, L., Graham, H., Haggar, P., Hamilton, I., Hartinger, S., Hess, J., Kelman, I., Kiesewetter, G., Kjellstrom, T., Kniveton, D., Lemke, B., Liu, Y., Lott, M., Lowe, R., Sewe, M. O., Martinez-Urtaza, J., Maslin, M., McAllister, L., McGushin, A., Jankin Mikhaylov, S., Milner, J., Moradi-Lakeh, M., Morrissey, K., Murray, K., Munzert, S., Nilsson, M., Neville, T., Oreszczyn, T., Owfi, F., Pearman, O., Pencheon, D., Phung, D., Pye, S., Quinn, R., Rabbaniha, M., Robinson, E., Rocklöv, J., Semenza, J. C., Sherman, J., Shumake-Guillemot, J., Tabatabaei, M., Taylor, J., Trinanes, J., Wilkinson, P., Costello, A., Gong, P., & Montgomery, H. (2019). The 2019 report of The Lancet Countdown on Health and Climate Change: Ensuring that the health of a child born today is not defined by a changing climate. Lancet, 394, 1836–1878. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(19)32596-6 WHO. (1948). Preamble to the Constitution of WHO as adopted by the International Health Conference, New York, 19 June–22 July 1946; signed on 22 July 1946 by the representatives of 61 states (Official Records of WHO no. 2, p. 100). World Health Organization (WHO). https://doi.org/10.1016/j.enbuild.2012.12.033 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.enbuild.2012.12.033 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.enpol.2014.12.002 https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199286294.001.0001 https://doi.org/10.1080/14649880500120491 https://doi.org/10.1080/14649880500120491 https://doi.org/10.1177/0021934706296188 https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(09)61716-5 https://doi.org/10.1089/env.2018.0041 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.scitotenv.2019.135038 https://doi.org/10.1177/0143624415621028 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.enbuild.2019.05.014 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.enpol.2019.111042 https://doi.org/10.1080/17565529.2013.828583 https://doi.org/10.5379/urbani-izziv-en-2018-29-supplement-005 https://doi.org/10.5379/urbani-izziv-en-2018-29-supplement-005 https://doi.org/10.1891/9780826190123.ap02 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.enpol.2011.11.093 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.envint.2015.09.010 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.envint.2015.09.010 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.enpol.2012.01.044 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jclepro.2018.08.314 https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(19)32596-6 Climate justice and the built environment428 Whyte, K. (2020). Too late for indigenous climate justice: Ecological and relational tipping points. WIREs Climate Change, 11, e603. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1002/wcc.603 Wilkinson, P., Smith, K. R., Davies, M., Adair, H., Armstrong, B. G., Barrett, M., Bruce, N., Haines, A., Hamilton, I., Oreszczyn, T., Ridley, I., Tonne, C., & Chalabi, Z. (2009). Public health benefits of strategies to reduce greenhouse- gas emissions: Household energy. Lancet, 374, 1917–1929. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(09)61713-X Willers, S. M., Jonker, M. F., Klok, L., Keuken, M. P., Odink, J., van den Elshout, S., Sabel, C. E., Mackenbach, J. P., & Burdorf, A. (2016). High resolution exposure modelling of heat and air pollution and the impact on mortality. Environment International, 89–90, 102–109. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.envint.2016.01.013 Wilson, B., & Chakraborty, A. (2013). The environmental impacts of sprawl: Emergent themes from the past decade of planning research. Sustainability, 5, 3302–3327. DOI: https://doi.org/10.3390/su5083302 Wolch, J. R., Byrne, J., & Newell, J. P. (2014). Urban green space, public health, and environmental justice: The challenge of making cities ‘just green enough’. Landscape and Urban Planning, 125, 234–244. DOI: https://doi. org/10.1016/j.landurbplan.2014.01.017 Woodcock, J., Edwards, P., Tonne, C., Armstrong, B. G., Ashiru, O., Banister, D., Beevers, S., Chalabi, Z., Chowdhury, Z., Cohen, A., Franco, O. H., Haines, A., Hickman, R., Lindsay, G., Mittal, I., Mohan, D., Tiwari, G., Woodward, A., & Roberts, I. (2009). Public health benefits of strategies to reduce greenhouse-gas emissions: urban land transport. Lancet, 374, 1930–1943. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(09)61714-1 WRI. (2020). World greenhouse gas emissions: 2016. World Resource Institute. Retrieved May 6, 2020, from https:// www.wri.org/resources/data-visualizations/world-greenhouse-gas-emissions-2016 Ziervogel, G., Pelling, M., Cartwright, A., Chu, E., Deshpande, T., Harris, L., Hyams, K., Kaunda, J., Klaus, B., Michael, K., Pasquini, L., Pharoah, R., Rodina, L., Scott, D., & Zweig, P. (2017). Inserting rights and justice into urban resilience: A focus on everyday risk. Environment and Urbanization, 29, 123–138. DOI: https://doi. org/10.1177/0956247816686905 How to cite this article: Klinsky, S., & Mavrogianni, A. (2020). Climate justice and the built environment. Buildings and Cities, 1(1), pp. 412–428. DOI: https://doi.org/10.5334/bc.65 Submitted: 27 June 2020 Accepted: 28 June 2020 Published: 14 July 2020 Copyright: © 2020 The Author(s). This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (CC-BY 4.0), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author and source are credited. See http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/. Buildings and Cities is a peer-reviewed open access journal published by Ubiquity Press OPEN ACCESS  https://doi.org/10.1002/wcc.603 https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(09)61713-X https://doi.org/10.1016/j.envint.2016.01.013 https://doi.org/10.3390/su5083302 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.landurbplan.2014.01.017 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.landurbplan.2014.01.017 https://doi.org/10.1016/S0140-6736(09)61714-1 https://www.wri.org/resources/data-visualizations/world-greenhouse-gas-emissions-2016 https://www.wri.org/resources/data-visualizations/world-greenhouse-gas-emissions-2016 https://doi.org/10.1177/0956247816686905 https://doi.org/10.1177/0956247816686905 https://doi.org/10.5334/bc.65 http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ 1. Introduction 2. Dimensions of climate injustice 3. The built environment and climate injustice 3.1. Long timeframes 3.2. Embedded accumulation 3.3. Wellbeing and built environment synergies 4. A capabilities approach 5. Multivalent justice 6. Contributions to knowledge of this special issue 7. Current challenges for the built environment 7.1. Governance and advocacy 7.2. Documentation and analysis 7.3. Training and capacity-building Acknowledgements Competing interests References Table 1 Table 2 Table 3 Table 4 work_2wnrh5mbafcgthdbjh3mnh3tki ---- Tim Forsyth Climate justice is not just ice Article (Accepted version) (Refereed) Original citation: Forsyth, Tim (2013) Climate justice is not just ice. Geoforum, online . ISSN 0016-7185 (In Press) DOI: 10.1016/j.geoforum.2012.12.008 © 2013 Elsevier B.V. This version available at: http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/48070/ Available in LSE Research Online: March 2013 LSE has developed LSE Research Online so that users may access research output of the School. Copyright © and Moral Rights for the papers on this site are retained by the individual authors and/or other copyright owners. Users may download and/or print one copy of any article(s) in LSE Research Online to facilitate their private study or for non-commercial research. You may not engage in further distribution of the material or use it for any profit-making activities or any commercial gain. You may freely distribute the URL (http://eprints.lse.ac.uk) of the LSE Research Online website. This document is the author’s final accepted version of the journal article. There may be differences between this version and the published version. You are advised to consult the publisher’s version if you wish to cite from it. http://www.lse.ac.uk/researchAndExpertise/Experts/profile.aspx?KeyValue=t.j.forsyth@lse.ac.uk http://www.journals.elsevier.com/geoforum http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.geoforum.2012.12.008 http://www.elsevier.com/ http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/48070/ 1 Climate justice is not just ice Tim Forsyth Department of International Development London School of Economics and Political Science Houghton Street London WC2A 2AE t.j.forsyth@ lse.ac.uk Published in: Geoforum (2014) mailto:t.j.forsyth@lse.ac.uk 2 Abstract Discussions about climate change and justice frequently employ dichotomies of procedural and distributive justice, and inter- and intra-generational justice. These distinctions, however, often fail to acknowledge the diverse experience of climate risks, or the contested nature of many proposed solutions. This paper argues for a reassessment of debates about climate justice based upon a greater diversity of risks and solutions such as integrating the reduction of social vulnerability simultaneously with mitigation. In effect, this implies reassessing the implicit use of Rawls’ model of justice as fair allocation of predefined risks and solutions, and instead considering Sen’s understanding of justice as inclusive debate about which risks require which solutions. Keywords: climate change, justice, development 3 Highlights ◦ The paper analyzes implicit assumptions made in many debates about climate change and justice, and distinguishes the common frames of procedural and distributive justice; and inter- and intra-generational justice. ◦ It argues that the analysis of justice needs to be applied to implicit assumptions about how climate change poses risks, and in turn how these create apparent solutions; and how far these are shared between more and less vulnerable people and countries. ◦ Models of just allocations of supposedly ‘global’ risks and solutions therefore need to be reassessed according to how far they reflect these diverse experiences. ◦ In turn, this analysis implies reassessing implicit Rawlsian approaches to justice abased on fair allocation, and exploring a more Senian approach of inclusive deliberation about which risks require which solutions. In climate change policy this implies reducing social vulnerability and building adaptive capacity in ways that are complementary to mitigation. 4 Climate justice is not just ice Environmental politics too often conflates what is urgent and distressing with what is just. In January 2011, newspapers reported how a female polar bear in the Arctic Ocean had swum continuously for an unprecedented nine days, losing her cub. Many commentators linked this event to how anthropogenic climate change is melting sea ice. ‘Polar bears …only occur in the Arctic where sea ice is found,’ said biologist George Durner, who conducted the survey. ‘By reducing greenhouse gas emissions, we can save sea ice habitat for polar bears.’1 At the same time, environmental activists in the USA were suing their government on behalf of polar bears. The government had, in late 2010, refused to amend the US Endangered Species Act in order to re-classify polar bears as ‘endangered’ rather than the less serious ‘threatened.’ O ne litigant declared: ‘The Obama administration delivered a lump of coal to the polar bear for Christmas. Ultimately, we are confident the court will …give polar bears the legal protection to which they are entitled.’ 2 Asking law courts to issue rights on behalf of polar bears is one example of how climate change and justice are now being linked. Yet, while the concerns about polar bears and many other aspects of climate change are indeed distressing and need attention, it does not always follow that imposing fast solutions is necessarily just. 1 http://www.onearth.org/article/polar-bears-nine-day-swim Accessed November 2012. 2 http://www.biologicaldiversity.org/news/press_releases/2010/polar-bear-12-23- 2010.html This statement is by the Center for Biological Diversity; other litigants include Greenpeace and the Natural Resources Defense Council. Accessed November 2012. http://www.onearth.org/article/polar-bears-nine-day-swim http://www.biologicaldiversity.org/news/press_releases/2010/polar-bear-12-23-2010.html http://www.biologicaldiversity.org/news/press_releases/2010/polar-bear-12-23-2010.html 5 Political processes need to pay more attention to how environmental problems – and solutions – are identified and seen as just. What’s wrong with justice? Environmental debates frequently use two main dichotomies to define justice. Yet, both overlap more than commonly thought. Both need to be rethought. The first dichotomy distinguishes distributive and procedural justice (Okereke, 2010a, b; Schlosberg, 2007; Sowers, 2007). Rawls’ (1971) classic discussion is most associated with distributive justice because it seeks a fair allocation to all parties if they adopt a procedure – called the ‘veil of ignorance’ – that asks them to imagine a fair allocation if no party can control the process of distribution. Sen’s (2009) positive critique of Rawls accepts this concept of justice, but also emphasizes procedure by arguing that rights of participation and inclusion are still evolving. The second common dichotomy is between intra-generational justice and inter- generational justice. The first protects the rights of future generations. The second seeks equality between current generations. Usually, these positions are linked to more developed societies and currently poorer countries (Redclift, 1987; Shue, 1992). Both of these dichotomies, however, fall down under two questions: who has defined ecological risks? What procedures can allow new participants to redefine risks? Rawls’ distributive approach is based on a procedure that does not question environmental goods and bads. And the distinction between inter- and intra- 6 generational justice is false because inter-generational justice is seeking the same rights to protect poorer societies’ future generations through securing access to development, with all its capacity to withstand environmental and other risks, today. Applying justice to environmental problems therefore is not simply based on allocating currently perceived risks and solutions, but on expanding how risks and solutions are defined. This is not a new activity. For years, much social science has emphasized the need to distinguish between protecting ecosystems as underlying entities, and in seeing the limitations in ecological concepts that have emerged to describe them. Problems emerge when these concepts and explanations are applied out of context (Forsyth, 2003, p. 6). Al Gore’s book, Earth in the Balance (1992, pp. 246-247) famously stated: ‘as it happens, the idea of social justice is inextricably linked in the Scriptures with ecology.’ This statement clearly justifies norms of social behaviour on the basis of fixed and unchanging ‘ecology.’ But Gore’s assertion does imply how social norms have defined ‘ecology.’ There is much in Gore’s vision of ecology that is a metaphor for acting responsibly within limits. Indeed, ecologists in the 1960s dubbed ecology ‘the subversive science’ because it represented a communal response to individualism. Eugene Odum (1964, p. 15) wrote ‘[ecology] deals with the structure and function of levels of organization beyond that of the individual,’ and Paul Sears (1964, p. 12) ‘by its very nature, ecology affords a continuing critique of man’s operations.’ Some people therefore use ecology as a framework for social justice. But the social influences on ecology – as a series of explanations of biophysical processes of cause-and-effect – are often only partially explored. 7 One example concerned how questions of including poorer countries were addressed under the Intergovernmental Panel on C limate C hange (IPCC) Working Group III. Some members were criticised in the 1990s for calculating the ‘value of life’ in accordance with national GDP – a procedure caricatured as valuing ‘one European as equal to ten C hinamen’ (Grubb, 1995, p. 471) (see also Vanderheiden, 2005). Yet, while policy analysts such as Michael Grubb sought to restore public trust in the IPCC by saying ‘there is a danger that economic evaluations… seek to enshrine in apparent objectivity the current value system of the practitioner’ (p. 472), other apparently objective claims go unexamined. Grubb, for example, starts his paper by focusing on ‘the increasingly pressing need for humanity to face the finite nature of the planet, and in doing so address the distributional issues relating to coping with the impacts of climate change’ (p. 463). In other words, Grubb wishes to assess the implicit assumptions in economic analysis of different nations’ vulnerability to climate change. But he does not consider how projections of climate change impacts themselves might also contain assumptions when applied to ‘humanity.’ How might the identification of impacts be based on equitable principles? And how does this affect the justice of proposed solutions? Rethinking distributive and procedural environmental justice Both the fixed basis of climate change impacts and the categories used to evaluate inclusiveness in climate change policy need to be rethought to achieve a fairer form of climate justice. The distribution of climate change solutions need to be defined in 8 ways that do not delegitimize appropriate economic growth; or which create additional risks from imposed policies. For example, in a recent World Bank publication, experts in the Environment Section called for a greater restoration of natural ecosystems as a way to enhance poorer people’s ability to cope with climate change impacts – an approach called ‘Ecosystem-based Approaches to Adaptation’ (World Bank, 2009). This report states: ‘natural ecosystems are resistant and resilient and provide a full range of goods and ecosystem services…’ (p. 47), but then claims ‘agriculture is already one of the greatest threats to natural ecosystems worldwide’ (p. 63). This statement does not acknowledge that successful agriculture feeds people, provides livelihoods, and can contribute to national GDP. Many richer countries better able to cope with climate change have partly grown their economies through agriculture. The United Nations Framework Convention on C limate C hange (UNFCCC) has also framed policies in terms of fast and low-cost mitigation of greenhouse gas concentrations rather than combining these actions with building social and economic resilience. ‘Adaptation’ to climate change has been seen mainly as reducing impacts of physical events such as floods and storms, rather than more development-oriented approaches such as diversifying livelihood options in affected regions (Burton, 2009). These approaches seek to address climate-change risk in terms of the additional biophysical events that can be linked to greater greenhouse-gas concentrations, rather than understand what social, economic, and political lack of capacity might make these physical changes problematic among poorer societies. Indeed, mitigation, 9 crudely and cheaply done, can enhance social vulnerability and hence incur additional social injustices (Marino and Ribot, 2012). Accordingly, as things stand, the UNFCCC Adaptation Fund is partly funded through a two percent levy on proceeds of certified emissions reduction units coming from the UNFCCC’s Clean Development Mechanism (C DM). Yet, critics from developing countries have often complained that the CDM has not delivered its original intention to enhance ‘sustainable development’ in accordance with the objectives o f the UNFCCC because it has largely focused on fast mitigation projects such as greenhouse gas destruction, rather than building livelihoods or local technological capacities in poorer countries (Boyd et al., 2009). Related projects that encourage fast- mitigation through carbon-offset forestry have also been claimed to lock up land with little immediate developmental benefit. The assumption is that fast mitigation or carbon sequestration will benefit all. But, mitigating global greenhouse gas concentrations with no attention to local social vulnerability to climate change or climate change policies might create additional risks for local people. According to (Kjellén, 2006, p. ix) ‘there is a risk that present adaptation strategies may reinforce vulnerability, if not properly conceived and legitimately implemented.’ An alternative approach is seeking solutions that mitigate climate change without compressing the rights to growth or the protection of vulnerable people. These kinds of options incorporate the essence of Rawls’ search for inclusive benefits, but require us to reconsider what benefits are being distributed. One possible example is the proposed AdMit financial instrument, which seeks investors for projects that can 10 combine mitigation and adaptation. 3 These projects can reduce greenhouse gas emissions as well as contribute to poverty reduction, development, and the sustainable use of resources. For example, urban waste management can mitigate climate change through methane capture and recycling, but also provide livelihoods if they employ local waste sorters (Forsyth, 2007). Indeed, new initiatives to integrate climate change policy, agriculture and food security 4 offer more possibilities for development dividends than sequestration alone. These kinds of activities do not just slow down physical rates of environmental change – that is to say, keep ice frozen. Instead, they also address additional facets of climate risk such as reducing the vulnerability o f poorer societies in dealing with climate events. They do not assume common benefits from a single goal of mitigation alone. Conclusion Debates about climate justice need to acknowledge the limitations of commonplace uses of phrases such as distributive and procedural justice. Distributive justice is only possible when there is something to distribute. Procedural justice includes how we define, as well as distribute, these objectives fairly. C limate change policy is not simply allocating solutions to melting ice. And an inclusive process is not just diversifying discussion of how to do this. So far, environmental politics does not consider deeply enough how, or with whose concerns, justice might be applied. Paavola et al. (2006, p. 267) wrote: ‘distributive 3 http://www.iied.org/climate-change/key- issues/economics-and-equity- adaptation/admit#about Accessed November 2012. 4 http://ccafs.cgiar.org/ Accessed November 2012. http://www.iied.org/climate-change/key-issues/economics-and-equity-adaptation/admit#about http://www.iied.org/climate-change/key-issues/economics-and-equity-adaptation/admit#about http://ccafs.cgiar.org/ 11 justice is unlikely to be able to provide a sufficient foundation for climate justice because of the heterogeneity of involved parties. Therefore, procedural justice is needed to underpin the legitimacy of climate change regime.’ But this statement does not acknowledge the heterogeneity of risks – from both climate change and proposed solutions – as well as heterogeneity of parties. Plus, Page (2006) and Schlosberg (2007) write positively about a Senian capability approach to environmental justice. Page (2006, p. 70) claims it can ‘preserve an environment that enables future persons to retain the same substantive freedoms to be healthy, well fed, and well clothed that their ancestors possessed.’ This statement shows that inter-generational justice is also intra-generational. But this assertion does not engage with how environmental limits to this process are defined, or how the potential benefits and disadvantages of proposed solutions are identified. Environmental justice therefore needs to consider which risks are to be addressed, and to engage with a policy process that is not simply framed by what appear to be urgent solutions to problems that are currently seen as distressing. In Rawlsian terms, an ideal solution should allow climate policies to address all concerns. But there is a need to look beyond commonplace discussions of distribution and procedure, and instead see how including more diverse values and priorities of affected people might influence what is seen as urgent. An ideal solution does not overlook some people’s concerns, or make their problems worse. ‘Justice’ is not simply a quick reference to acting ethically, but rather a source of reasoning for what is considered legitimate. At worse, it can become ‘a mere cover 12 for self- interested bargaining’ (Okereke, 2010, p. 463). The Rawlsian model of distributive justice should not be applied without reconsidering what it assumes are the risks to be distributed. We should not let an epistemological, ‘veil of ignorance’ deceive us that what we think are natural limits or appropriate solutions are universally applicable or without potential negative impacts on others. REFERENCES Boyd, E., Hultman, N., Roberts, T., Corbera, E., Cole, J., Bozmoski, A., Ebeling, J., Tippman, R., Mann, P., Brown, K., Liverman, D., 2009. Reforming the CDM for sustainable development: lessons learned and policy futures. Environmental science and policy 12, 820-831. Burton, I., 2009. Climate change and the adaptation deficit, in: Schipper, E.L., Burton, I. (Eds.), The Earthscan Reader on Adaptation to C limate Change. Earthscan, London, pp. 89-98. Forsyth, T., 2003. Critical Political Ecology : The Politics of Environmental Science. Routledge, London ; New York. Forsyth, T., 2007. Promoting the “Development Dividend” of C limate Technology Transfer: Can Cross-sector Partnerships Help? World Development 35 (10), 1684- 1698. Gore, A., 1992. Earth in the Balance: Forging a New Common Purpose. Earthscan, London. 13 Grubb, M., 1995. Seeking fair weather? Ethics and the international debate on climate change. International Affairs 71, 462-496. Kjellén, B., 2006. Foreword, in: Adger, W., Paavola, J., S., H., Mace, M. (Eds.), Fairness in Adaptation to Climate Change. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp. vii-x. Marino, E., Ribot, J., 2012. Special Issue Introduction: Adding insult to injury: Climate change and the inequities of climate intervention. Global Environmental Change 22 (2), 323-328. Odum, E., 1964. The new ecology. Bioscience 14 (7), 14-16. Okereke, C., 2010a. C limate justice and the international regime. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Climate Change 1, 462-474. Okereke, C., 2010b. Global Justice and Neoliberal Environmental Governance. Routledge, London. Paavola, J., Adger, W., Huq, S., 2006. Multifaceted justice in adaptation to climate change, in: Adger, W., Paavola, J., Huq, S., Mace, M. (Eds.), Fairness in Adaptation to Climate Change. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp. 263-278. Page, E., 2006. Climate change, Justice and Future Generations. Elgar, Northampton, MA. Rawls, J., 1971. A Theory of Justice. Belknap Press, Cambridge, MA. Redclift, M., 1987. Sustainable Development: Exploring the Contradictions. Routledge, London. Schlosberg, D., 2007. Defining Environmental Justice: Theories, Movements, and Nature. Oxford University Press, Oxford. Sears, P.B., 1964. Ecology – a subversive subject. Bioscience 14 (7), 11-13. Sen, A., 2009. The Idea of Justice. Allen Lane, London. 14 Shue, H., 1992. The unavoidability of justice, in: Hurrell, A., K ingsbury, B. (Eds.), The international politics of the environment. O xford University Press, O xford, pp. 373-397. Sowers, J., 2007. The many injustices of climate change. Global Environmental Politics 7 (4), 140-146. Vanderheiden, S., 2005. Missing the forest for the trees: Justice and environmental economics. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 8 (1), 51- 69. World Bank, 2009. Convenient Solutions to an Inconvenient Truth: Ecosystem-Based Approaches to Climate Change. World Bank, Washington. Forsyth_Climate_justice_is_not_just_ice_2013_cover Forsyth_Climate_justice_is_not_just_ice_2013_author work_2z4iqgkmy5bf7cki757tfx7yoy ---- Images of Justice Images of Justice Lela P. Love t Strong and appealing visions shape lives and actions profoundly. Con- sider how Martin Luther King's I Have a Dream vision, aligned with his phi- losophy of nonviolence, personal courage and self-sacrifice, propelled the ulti- mate integration of public facilities in America. In contrast, the Black Panther symbol and Black Power rhetoric energized an entirely different movement to address repression and the aftermath of a historical era that embraced the en- slavement of large groups of people. Or consider how Gandhi used nonvio- lent protest in India to shift power from "haves" to "have nots" in a manner that was inconceivable before or without his vision. The strength, clarity and appeal of different images of justice help deter- mine the acceptability and success of the processes associated with those images. For any system of justice to be acceptable to parties who believe that an injustice has occurred, the ideal behind and the workings of the process it- self must be consistent with a clear and compelling vision of fairness. While vision and reality can part company from time to time, buffeted by the exigencies of particular situations, one cannot stray far from the heart or soul of an enterprise without jeopardizing its fundamental health and well- being. In an effort to capture the vision behind the three major dispute resolu- tion processes, this essay will present an image of a judge, an arbiter and a mediator. The analysis will note how current practices, in many respects, have strayed from these images and point out the danger of having a process di- vorced from a compelling "justice" rationale. Litigation Standing straight and tall in public places, a blindfolded woman holds up scales. Since she is blindfolded, she cannot be swayed by gender, race, wealth, or other influences or advantages that one party might hold. On her scales, disputing parties rest their case: the best they can muster for them- 1. Lela P. Love is a clinical professor of law and director of the Kukin Program for Con- flict Resolution at Benjamin N. Cardozo School of Law. This essay is dedicated to individuals who have in their careers or personal lives stepped forward to rescue and revive victims of the inexorable working of systems of "justice." Most notably, in my own experience, Barry Scheck (Cardozo's Innocence Project) and Russell \Veatherspoon. Thanks to Dan vcitz. Simeon Baum and Martin Love for thoughtful comments and suggestions. selves and the worst they can present about the other side. The matter is weighed on these scales in public view, and the balance resolves the matter. The scales themselves get more precisely balanced after each weighing, after each case. The weight and moment of precise and particular factors are calibrated, and the blindfolded lady announces how much factors weigh, this time, and for all time. Should a party suspect that the scales were out of balance or the blind- fold had been lifted, he may appeal to higher authorities to test the integrity of the process. This lady is accessible to all, rich and poor alike. Like the other com- manding woman standing at the Golden Door in NYC harbor with a torch of liberty, she says, "Give me your tired, your poor, your humbled masses yearning . . . " And if one party invokes her aid, the other must answer and counter-weight the scale, or risk an unfavorable verdict. He must also risk the power behind this blindfolded figure-the power of the state to take and give property and liberty. If Martin Luther King were delivering an I Have a Dream Speech about the process this blindfolded woman symbolizes it might sound something like this: I have a dream that every person can bring a claim to a public place and an intelligent, experienced and impartial third party chosen or appointed by democratic process will as- sess the facts, apply the law and determine the outcome. The whole world will watch to keep this forum honest. I have a dream that this forum will be accessible, the procedures straightforward, efficient and understandable, the costs appropriate, and the determination speedy. I have a dream that judges will help define, clarify, and broadcast our public norms by focusing all their attention on the explication of the law as it intersects with the facts of each case. I have a dream that every judge is charged with ensuring that his or her corner of the dispute resolution universe offers a fair and clean playing field. No judge will try to co- erce settlement by threatening parties with onerous outcomes. Every judge will treat each party with courtesy and respect. Arbitration Wise, sophisticated, trusted, and honored in his community, the arbitrator is chosen by the parties who can agree that whatever such a person decides is just. The arbitrator does not wear blindfolds because the parties trust his dis- cretion. On the other hand, the arbitrator cannot meet privately with a party, because the parties do not trust each other. [Vol. 1: 29, 2000] PEPPERDINE DISPUTE RESOLUTION LAW JOURNAL The arbitrator stands, aloof from the parties, arms folded in skepticism, but listening attentively for each clue which will piece together the puzzle of facts he must see clearly. The gift the arbitrator gives the parties is a prompt decision informed by his expertise in the particular arena. His decision is bound to favor one party over the other, but his quick and precise award will allow the parties to move on with their lives and their businesses. There is no appeal from this arbitrator because, in choosing him, the par- ties chose to live with what he decides. Thus, the power of the arbitrator is immense, once conferred by the parties, and is further bolstered by the blind- folded lady who will ensure that his awards are honored. If a party were delivering an I Have a Dream speech about arbitration, it might sound something like this: I have a dream that I can create mV own forum and choose my own arbiter I have a dream that a special and wise expert in the particular arena of the dispute. whom I trust, can hear my dispute, and I can accept his or her judgment and put the matter behind me, win or lose. I have a dream that my dispute can be resolved in a private place, so that the indignities, dangers, and damages of a public forum do not compound the upset and anger of being in conflict I have a dream that arbitrators are charged with ensuring that their corner of the dispute resolution universe offers a fair and clean playing field. No arbitrator will try to coerce settlement by threatening parties with onerous outcomes. Every arbitrator will treat each party with courtesy and respect. Mediation In this image one sees a figure sitting with the parties, her hands reach- ing towards each of them as if to support them in telling their tale or to cau- tion them in listening to each other to weigh the matter more carefully. It is also possible that her outreached hands are pointing to the parties to remind them of their responsibility for dealing thoughtfully with their situation and each other, understanding the opportunities and risks inherent in various choices, and summoning their creativity in addressing the conflict. The figure is not alone or aloof. Her outstretched arms form a bridge be- tween the parties, so that communication and positive energy can flow again. Her presence is a catalyst setting in motion the potential that the parties hold. Unlike the blindfolded lady, the mediator sees all that is offered unpro- tected by formal procedure or rules of evidence. Unlike the arbitrator or the judge, the mediator may meet with the parties together or listen to them pri- vately so that each nuance of meaning and each atom of possibility are cap- tured and offered back, in their most palatable form, for the parties. The mediator's features are hazy, since the focus and light remains on the disputing parties. Her presence, however, exudes optimism, respect, and confidence in the parties' capacity. She brings an energetic and urgent sense that justice can be done by the parties' own hands. If a mediator were delivering an I Have a Dream speech about media- tion, it might sound something like this: I have a dream that I can offer a safe and private place for parties in conflict to come and sit together at a table. I have a dream that I can help disputing parties tell their stories and explain their feel- ings and values to each other in a manner that might enable one another to understand more clearly and perhaps build or preserve their relationship. I have a dream that the dispute can be resolved in a private place, so that the indignities, dangers, and damages of a public forum do not compound the upset and anger of being in conflict. I have a dream that I can assist parties in discovering or constructing outcomes that seem reasonable and optimal to them. How do current practices and trends part company with the blindfolded lady? In 1853, in his novel Bleak House, Charles Dickens sounded an alarm about the state of the courts: "This is the Court of Chancery . . .which gives to monied might the means abundantly of wearying out the right; which so exhausts finances, patience, courage, hope; so over- throws the brain and breaks the heart; that there is not an honorable man among its prac- titioners who would not give-who does not often give-the warning, 'Suffer any wrong that can be done you, rather than come here.' "2 Similar sentiments have been echoed by eminent jurists and scholars. In 1982, Chief Justice Warren Burger summarized dissatisfaction with litigation: "Our system is too costly, too painful, too destructive, too inefficient for a truly civilized people."' 3 In addition to the shortcomings pointed out by Dick- ens and Burger, other trends jeopardize the accuracy and integrity of the im- age presented by the blindfolded "justice". For example, the system of plea bargaining in criminal cases has virtually supplanted trial by a jury of peers, 2. CHARLEs DIcKENs, Bleak House (first published in 1853), Penguin Classics 1971, at 51. 3. Warren Burger, Isn't There a Better Way?: Annual Report on the State of the Judiciary, Remarks at the Mid-Year Meeting of the American Bar Association (Jan. 24, 1982), in 68 A.B.A. J. 274, 275 (1982). [Vol. 1: 29, 2000] PEPPERDINE DISPUTE RESOLUTION LAW JOURNAL which places heavier charges, stiffer penalties, and the displeasure of the prosecutor and judge on the scales for any defendant so brash as to claim in- nocence and seek trial. Also, judges must manage and move heavy dockets, which places a premium on administrative and management skills over and above qualities and capacities necessary to weigh matters precisely and to ar- ticulate norms eloquently. 4 Finally, the expectation that judges become mediators of their own cases tempts the blindfolded lady, under the guise of "mediator", to coerce the parties into settlement out of fear of displeasing this mediator-judge.5 What happened to the wise arbiter and his efficient process? By the 1990's scholars and practitioners were saying that arbitration had been ru- ined.6 The key features of arbitration-simplicity, low cost, finality, and speed-have been eroded by lawyers who bring in the cumbersome attributes of litigation-formality, delay, great quantities of paper, motions, appeals, and high cost. 7 Additionally, the proliferation of arbitration clauses in employment and consumer agreements, places where it is unlikely that there is meaningful consent to an alternative form of conflict resolution, undermines the contrac- tual feature of arbitration as a process emanating from and built by the parties themselves. So arbitration shifts to being a litigation look-alike, but without the protections of litigation's publicly chosen judge, public forum, and ap- peals process or arbitration's protections of truly informed party consent and party-chosen neutral(s). What is happening to mediation? As lawyers are taking training pro- grams geared towards "spinning the mediator" to gain a competitive advan- 4. See State of the States: Dispute Resolution in the Courts. ruE CAwRozo 0.NIw' JoUtR. NAT Op Coiucr REsoLtrrov, wivcardozo.yuedulcojcr, quoting Daniel Weitz, N.Y.S. ADR Co- ordinator, stating: "Judges are often measured, reviewed and critiqued by the degree to which they can move cases along within certain time frames... A certain 'judicial badge of honor' has even evolved for those judges who have developed a reputation for being 'great settlers.' 5. See James J. Alfini, Risk of Coercion Too Great, DsUTm REsoLmtuou MAGAmE (Fall 1999) at 11 (concluding that judges should not mediate cases assigned to them for trial). 6. See generally L.EONARD L RiSKIN AND JAMEs E. WESmROOK, DtstM REsoLno. AND LAwyrRs (21d ed.) 585-588 (noting ways in which arbitration is becoming more like litigation and is losing its essential characteristics) and Kimberlee K. Kovach and Lela P. Love. Mapping Mediation: The Risks of Riskin's Grid, 3 Htv. NEG. L Rv. 71. at 90-91 and accompanying footnotes, (discussing how arbitration has lost much of its appeal due to becoming more like litigation). 7. See id. tage, and mediation (as arbitration has done) is becoming more legalized 8, mediation, too, might stray from the image of a mediator as a bridge between the real parties. For example, in many programs parties file pre-mediation confidential briefs with the mediator which often resemble litigation papers, rather than having features specifically targeted towards mediation. There is also a tendency for attorneys to choose (on behalf of their clients) mediators with extensive litigation or judicial experience who are expected to provide case evaluations, transforming mediation into an adjudicatory process.9 A log- ical result of these trends may be that, like arbitration, mediation may move away from its roots and become an attorney-dominated, adversarial and ever more costly proceeding.'0 In 1966 Martin Luther King and Stokely Carmichael participated in the "March Against Fear", a walk from Memphis, Tennessee to Jackson, Missis- sippi organized by leaders of the civil rights movement. During that march, tension developed between King and Carmichael. King was committed to nonviolence. At one point the members of the Mississippi Highway Patrol shoved demonstrators, and Carmichael bitterly complained. An activist com- mitted to nonviolence teased Carmichael about his reaction: "You see, Stokely, the difference between you and the military is that a soldier has sin- gleness of purpose. When you get shoved you get confused. If you're really not nonviolent, you ought to get a gun and be a guerilla."" Before the march was over, Carmichael's group broke away from the others and adopted the slogan, "Black Power!" Many date this incident as the beginning of the Black Power Movement.' 2 8. See The Director as Futurist: Jack Hanna Previews 'Coming Attractions' in ADR, 4 ADR REPORT no. 4,at 3-4 (Feb. 2000)(noting that mediation is becoming more adversarial, hostile and confrontational). 9. In a survey of 600 members of the Hillsborough County (Fla.) Trial Lawyers Section by Martha J. Cook, Esq., in which 160 lawyers responded, 90% of the respondents indicated that they would prefer "evaluative" mediation. See Martha J. Cook, Hillsborough Survey (1997); see also Kovach & Love, supra note 6, footnotes 70 and 72 and accompanying text at 85 (discussing an attorney preference for "evaluative" mediation). 10. See Mary W. Holden, As Courts Overflow, Mediation Flourishes, CHICAGO LAWYER. Mar. 1997, at 20 (quoting James J. Alfini: "Arguably what happened to arbitration is that law- yers got a hold of it and turned it into a mini-adjudication. I worry that's going to happen to me- diation as lawyers colonize the field."). See generally Kovach & Love, supra note 6, at 92-98 (discussing the mutation of mediation). 11. Attributed to Rev. James M. Lawson, Jr., who has been termed by historians the non- violent strategist of the civil rights movement and was a close advisor to Martin Luther King. Unpublished manuscript, written for the L.A. Time Magazine by historian Spencie Love, Profile of James M. Lawson, Jr. (1998)(on file with author). 12. Id. [Vol. 1: 29, 2000] PEPPERDINE DISPUTE RESOLUTION LAW JOURNAL Like Stokely Carmichael confronted by brutal Mississippi officers, the blindfolded woman might get confused when she is charged with settling cases and managing overwhelming dockets. When we impose an arbitrator on parties who have not accepted that person as their decision-maker, the ratio- nale for the process becomes muddled. They will be confused as to why the process is "just." When we ask a mediator to stand back and judge the mat- ter, she will get confused. We need to keep the images clear and true so that, at least, we have guide stars and, at best, we have meaningful alternatives when we seek systems for responding to the crisis of conflict. In this new millennium, we should continue to build novel processes, like the mini-trial, the summary jury trial, neutral experts, non-binding arbi- tration, medene (mediation combined with early neutral evaluation), arb-med and med-arb, 13 but each new process must have a clear rationale and norms of practice which place it in the constellation of processes offering parties a cohejrent method of achieving justice. Since we already have powerful, work- able images and processes, we must guard and develop our systems, proce- dures, protocols, and trained skilled practitiohers to deliver on the promises these ideas and symbols hold out. We must block trends that run counter to formative visions. Whether our processes are pure or hybrids, to keep their power they must keep close to their heart and soul, as King and Gandhi kept close to the visions they held dear. The processes and the practitioners in them must remember their point of origin. 13. For summary definitions and descriptions of these and other dispute resolution processes, see RisKiN & WVEsTBROOK. supra note 6. at 1-11. 36 work_33xdbe5lh5hv7owwtacsqiuwem ---- Roland Kostić1 The Hugo Valentin Centre Uppsala University Original scientific paper UDK: 316.48(497.6) Received 14 May 2012 DOI: 10.2298/SOC1204649K TRANSITIONAL JUSTICE AND RECONCILIATION IN BOSNIA-HERZEGOVINA: WHOSE MEMORIES, WHOSE JUSTICE? Tranziciona pravda i pomirenje u Bosni i Hercegovini: čije uspomene, čija pravda? ABSTRACT This paper shows that transitional justice initiatives such as the trials at the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia and the State Court of Bosnia and Herzegovina, the Commission for Srebrenica and the establishment of accurate statistics on deaths during the conflict have had only a limited impact on inter-group reconciliation in Bosnia and Herzegovina. Popular attitudes towards these initiatives are captured in surveys conducted in 2005 and 2010. The results are not surprising given that the absence, due to the level of external regulation and control, of a politics of post-Dayton state-building means that domestic politics takes place in an arena of dealing with the past. The international community legitimised the three prevalent conflict narratives as a way of achieving a peace settlement in Dayton. These communal narratives were used in the peace-building phase by the local elites to defend concessions gained during negotiations and to oppose changes imposed by external supervisors of the Dayton Peace Accords. This has transformed the debate over the recent conflict from a transitional process of coming to terms with the past to a permanent state of affairs. This process precludes reconciliation in terms of mutual acknowledgment of suffering and a nuanced understanding of the causes and dynamics of the violent conflict. KEY WORDS transitional justice; politics; reconciliation; Bosnia and Herzegovina; ICTY, OHR APSTRAKT U ovom radu se pokazuje da inicijative u domenu tranzicione pravde, kao što su suđenja pred Međunarodnim krivičnim sudom za bivšu Jugoslaviju i Državnim sudom Bosne i Hercegovine, Komisija za Srebrenicu i stvaranje tačne statističke baze podataka o poginulima tokom sukoba imaju samo ograničeno dejstvo na pomirenje među nacionalnim zajednicama u Bosni i Hercegovini. Stavovi javnosti prema tim inicijativama pokazuju se u anketama sprovedenim 2005. i 2010. godine. Rezultati ne iznenađuju s obzirom na to da, zahvaljujući visokom nivou spoljne regulacije i kontrole, izostaje politika postdejtonske izgradnje države, što znači da se domaća politika odvija u areni suočavanja s prošlošću. Međunarodna zajednica je legitimisala tri preovlađujuća narativa o sukobu, kao način da se postigne mirovni sporazum u Dejtonu. Te narative, vezane za nacionalne zajednice, koristile su lokalne elite tokom faze izgradnje mira, kako bi odbranile usputke koje su postigle tokom ———— 1 roland.kostic@valentin.uu.se 650 SOCIOLOGIJA, Vol. LIV (2012), N° 4 pregovora i usprotivili se izmenama koje su nametale spoljne instance nadgledanja Dejtonskog mirovnog sporazuma. Na taj način debata o nedavnom konfliktu pretvorena je iz tranzicionog procesa suočavanja s prošlošću u trajno stanje stvari. Taj proces onemogućava pomirenje u smislu uzajamnog priznanja patnje i nijansiranog razumevanja uzroka i dinamike nasilnog sukoba. KLJUČNE REČI tranziciona pravda; politika; pomirenje; Bosna i Hercegovina; ICTY; OHR Introduction2 Negotiating comprehensive peace agreements became popular after the end of the Cold War (Vinjamuri and Boesenecker, 2007:5). In the period 1989 to 2011, 178 peace agreements were signed in support of various diplomatic initiatives (Wallensteen, 2012: 81). Policymakers and scholars have argued that although the early, less comprehensive peace agreements were able to end the violence, they seldom dealt with the societal divisions in post-war societies (Borer, 2006:5). As a consequence, in addition to the range of state-building measures, various transitional justice mechanisms have been incorporated into peace agreements in order to facilitate sustainable post-accord peace-building (Kostić, 2007: 31–34; Kostić, 2008:205; Vinjamuri and Boesenecker, 2007: 5). It has been argued that state- building coupled with measures to deal with past atrocities and the issue of selective views of the past can lead to national reconciliation and lasting stability (EU, 2004; Huyse, 2005; Lederach, 1997, Serwer, 2012). In broad terms, a number of studies have focused on the need to acknowledge past events as a condition for parties to be able to reconcile and build a common future. Huyse, for example, discusses the goal of reconciliation in terms of reparation for past injustices, and the building or rebuilding of non-violent relationships between individuals and between communities (Huyse, 2005:19). According to such views, restoring a broken moral order requires that justice is seen to be done (Williams and Scharf, 2002: 16–22; Huyse, 2005: 97–98).3 In a similar vein, Priscilla Hayner writes that “reconciliation implies building or rebuilding relationships today that are not haunted by the conflicts and hatreds of yesterday” (Hayner, 2001: 161). Hayner also suggests a number of indicators for establishing the level of reconciliation in a society. These include how the past is integrated and spoken about between former enemies, whether contradictory versions of the past have been reconciled and whether relationships are based on the present or the past. ———— 2The author would like to thank to Tomislav Dulić, Vanessa Pupovac, Alexandra Kent, Jens Sörensen, Fredrik Söderbaum, Julian Reid, Giorgio Shani, Henning Melber, Kristine Höglund, and Karin Aggestam for their comments on earlier drafts of this paper. The paper has benefited from generous support from the Swedish Research Council. 3According to its proponents, the possible benefits of retributive justice include avoiding private revenge, the prevention of a return to power by the perpetrators, fulfilling an obligation to victims, individualising guilt, and strengthening legitimacy and the democratic process. Roland Kostić: Transitional Justice and Reconciliation in Bosnia-Herzegovina... 651 The prevailing logic suggests that while a combination of good governance and constitutional and legal equality can encourage inter-group cooperation in the post-war period (EU, 2004; Rigby, 2001:180), transitional justice measures such as tribunals and truth commissions generate accountability for war crimes, individualise accountability and facilitate a comprehensive understanding of the past (Rigby, 2001: 180; Williams and Scharf, 2001:16–22; Huyse, 2005). Together, these measures are believed to facilitate processes of inter-group and interpersonal reconciliation, which are considered the pillars of sustainable peacebuilding (Williams and Scharf, 2001; EU, 2004; Jeong, 2005: 12). However, numerous criticisms of transitional justice efforts have emerged in recent scholarly debate. Proponents of incorporating transitional justice mechanisms into a broader externally promoted liberal peace-building agenda argue that negotiations and power sharing among warring parties work against the idea of delivering truth and justice to the victims (Wiliams and Scharf, 2001). They suggest that external parties should be clearer from the outset about who is the victim and who is perpetrator, and impose just solutions to the conflict (see Wiliams and Scharf, 2001: 12–14). The other side of the debate criticises the inclusion of transitional justice mechanisms in a wider strategy of externally run liberal peace-building projects. As Sriram (2009: 98) points out, transitional justice solutions imposed by Western peace-builders may result in a primary focus on legal accountability. This may be problematic as an approach since it focuses primarily on individual rights and responsibilities and might not be seen as just in societies that emphasise group and community identity (Sriram, 2009: 100). In addition, it has been argued that the external imposition of the exercise of universal jurisdiction, such as was the case with the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia (ICTY) and remains so with the International Criminal Court (ICC), can disrupt delicate domestic peace and reconciliation processes (Sriram, 2009: 100; Hayden, 2011: 313). It has also been suggested that while not facilitating domestic reconciliation, such practices financially benefit international human rights lawyers and domestic human rights agencies (Hayden, 2011: 313, 325; Bilić, 2011: 305, 309) as well as local political elites (Subotić, 2009: 45–46). This critique of externally imposed transitional justice and its impact on reconciliation is important, but it does not fully explore the link between external peace-building and transitional justice, or how these affect processes of reconciliation in societies emerging from war. I argue in this paper that the problem is complex and is linked to a broader change in our understanding and the practice of conflict resolution since the end of the Cold War. Initially, conflict resolution was based on the idea of assisting the primary parties by means of mediation to arrive at their own solutions to peacefully resolving disputes (Galtung, 2012). However, since the end of the Cold War there has been an 652 SOCIOLOGIJA, Vol. LIV (2012), N° 4 increasing tendency for powerful third-party interventions and the hegemonic imposition on conflict-ridden societies of a liberal peace-building formula based on institution building, elections and market-oriented economic reforms (Ericsson and Kostić, 2013). The primary parties to the conflict are usually included as participants in the process, but often have little influence over its content or outcome (Chandler, 2006, 2011; Kostić, 2011). This external-local hybridity regarding the ownership is particularly relevant for a contemporary understanding of transitional justice and its impact on reconciliation. I argue that the inclusion of the primary parties legitimises their specific views on the causes and dynamics of conflict, that is, it legitimises the opposing beliefs about the source of the incompatibility. At the same time, external parties often have their own perspective on the conflict and proposals for its resolution—including a particular transitional justice mechanism (see Dragović- Soso and Gordy, 2010: 203; Krampe, 2013). This type of interaction places transitional justice practice in the realm of politics, in which differing narratives and framings of the past compete for dominance, because establishing the truth about a conflict legitimises what is seen as just and moral in the post-war political context (see Williams and Scharf, 2001: 12). In other words, instead of agreement on past events and a mutual acknowledgment of suffering, the dynamics of such hybrid processes result in a policy of policing the past and in preserving the conflicting believes about that past held by the primary parties. In such a societal context, the work and results of various transitional justice initiatives are viewed primarily from the perspective of existing collective narratives and political framings that legitimise and link selective group perspectives to the post-war situation. This theoretical argument is explored further using unique survey data from 2005 (n=2500) and 2010 (n=1500) on the popular perceptions of a number of transitional justice initiatives in Bosnia and Herzegovina. The next section briefly explores the linkages between negotiating peace agreements and the salience of selective group narratives, using the case of Bosnia and Herzegovina since the Dayton Peace Accords (DPA). I examine the issue of the legitimacy of conflicting collective memories in the context of peace-building, and discuss the impact this has on the reproduction and salience of mutually exclusive collective memory and the perceptions of justice that stem from it. In the sections that follow, I present group perceptions of the conflict in Bosnia and Herzegovina, and examine the goals and impact of the ICTY, the State Court of Bosnia and Herzegovina, the Commission of Srebrenica, and the Research and Documentation centre on inter-group reconciliation. The final section provides conclusions. The Role of Group Narratives about War in Peace-building It has been suggested that the socio-psychological infrastructure that evolves during an intractable conflict plays a determinative role in its development and Roland Kostić: Transitional Justice and Reconciliation in Bosnia-Herzegovina... 653 continuation, and later in its resolution and reconciliation (Bar-Tal, 2007:1432). There are three key elements of socio-psychological infrastructure: collective memories, an ethos of conflict and collective emotional orientation (Bar-Tal, 2007: 1432). Collective memory makes sense of the past as a function of the present state of the community’s existence, especially in the context of its confrontation with rival groups(s). Thus, collective memory usually has some basis in genuine past events, but is biased, selective and distorted in ways that meet the group’s present needs. Such memories tend to omit certain facts, insert doubtful ones and offer a purposive interpretation of past events (Bar-Tal, 2007: 1437). Yet, collective memory is treated by many community members as a truthful account of the past and a valid history of their group. In addition, communities evolve a narrative about the present—an ethos consisting of central societal beliefs dealing with the group’s orientation both at present and in the future (Bar-Tal, 2000: 139–142). Together, these provide a coherent and meaningful picture of the causes of conflict, its evolution and its link to the present (Devine-Wright, 2003). In the case of Bosnia and Herzegovina, contending Bosniak, Bosnian Serb and Bosnian Croat ethno-national narratives and believes about the political incompatibility emerged in a wider context of the dissolution of the former Yugoslavia. The war and its dynamics played a crucial role in the evolution of existing ethno-national framings of the root causes of the conflict, and resulted in three mutually exclusive ethno-national narratives about the role of their own community and the role of others in the Bosnian war. The US-led Western peace- making initiative and the signing of the Dayton Peace Accords in November 1995 brought an end to inter-ethnic violence (see Kostić, 2009). The way in which the violence ended, however, has had a huge impact on the further recognition of collective narratives about the war. The externally negotiated peace was a compromise which meant that there was no victorious side and no defeated side (Williams and Schafer, 2001:160–161). In addition, by having the political representatives of the Bosniak, Bosnian Serb and Bosnian Croat communities participated in peace talks, the US-led international mediators, at least in part, acknowledged and legitimised the prevailing collective memories of wartime events in order to get to a peace settlement.4 However, in terms of the interpretation and implementation of the Dayton Peace Accords, the US-led international community assumed total control of the process from the beginning. By controlling the political process, the Constitutional Court and the implementation mechanism through bodies such as the Office of the High Representative(OHR) and the Peace Implementation Council (PIC), US and ———— 4However, there was little agreement on the issue internationally. For the key international power, the US, the war was a case of genocidal violence against the Bosniak population. However, other major powers such as France, the UK, Russia and Germany to a lesser or greater extent divided responsibility between the three sides (for more see Wiliams and Scharf, 2001: 64-87). 654 SOCIOLOGIJA, Vol. LIV (2012), N° 4 EU policymakers believed that they could steer the evolution of the Dayton Peace Accords (Kostić, 2011). Throughout the process, the US-led international community sought to remove ’backward-looking’ provisions dealing with group rights and to promote ‘forward-looking’ provisions dealing with the rights of individuals (for more see Nystuen, 2005: 239–51; O’Brien, 2005: 108–109). Although formally involved, the Bosnia and Herzegovina political elites representing local constituencies were until recently de facto excluded from any meaningful influence over politics or the economy in Bosnia and Herzegovina (Chandler, 2005; Hayden, 2005).5 Presented with a situation of peace-building without politics, while facing continued external demands for the evolution of the Dayton Peace Accords, more or less democratically elected domestic elites developed a range of responses. The most prominent feature of this external-domestic dynamic was the engagements in a politics of the past (see Kostić, 2007: 361). In order to justify their own visions of the past and relate these to the present, political elites engaged in commemorations of tragic events, and continued to propagate their own side’s views about the causes the war, the hostility of the “other” and their own victimhood, while staying beyond the reach of the OHR.6 Reframing past events also allowed them to claim that the original content of the Dayton Peace Accords legitimized their particular position. In this ongoing process, relinquishing one’s own collective wartime narrative and accepting that of your opponent is a political defeat for the community rather than a step towards reconciliation. The predominant attitudes to and perceptions of the war and wartime events, as well as the political bickering about specific wartime events raised numerous questions for external supervisors of the Dayton Peace Accords. Could a common state be built without reconciling diametrically opposed collective narratives regarding the causes of war and the role different groups were perceived to have played? Could peace be built without delivering justice to victims of violence, and while the perpetrators of gross violations of human rights remained at large? Finally, could former enemies trust and respect each other without a minimum of mutual understanding of the past? In the light of the complex challenges posed by attitudes and the lingering sense of injustice in the aftermath of Bosnian war, a number of external transitional justice mechanisms were promoted to facilitate inter-group reconciliation and deal with the selective collective memories of the three communities. The most important were the International Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia in The Hague, the War Crimes Chamber of the State Court of Bosnia and Herzegovina, the Research and ———— 5 For the views of the Bosnia and Herzegovina elites on their ownership and participation in post- Dayton politics see Kostić (2007: 183–192). 6 For examples of the attitudes of Bosnia and Herzegovina politicians to the past see Kostić (2007: 243–280). Roland Kostić: Transitional Justice and Reconciliation in Bosnia-Herzegovina... 655 Documentation Centre in Sarajevo and the Commission on Srebrenica. The following section discusses some the key findings on the popular attitudes concerning these initiatives. Communal Memories of War in Bosnia and Herzegovina Before presenting and discussing the findings on the contributions of various transitional justice initiatives to truth and justice, it is important to establish the state of collective memory about the war in Bosnia and Herzegovina. In order to do so, I use findings from surveys I conducted in cooperation with IPSOS in 2005 and 2010. Respondents were asked their views on the role of their own group and the character of the war, and to name the defensive military force in the conflict. Asked in 2005 if they agreed with the statement “my people have fought only defensive wars”, an overwhelming majority of Bosniaks, 85.3 per cent, Serbs, 76.2 per cent, and Croats, 75.9 per cent, strongly agreed. Although the number of those strongly agreeing with the statement fell in 2010, especially among Bosnian Serb respondents where 54.7 per cent totally agreed, the view that members of their own community fought a defensively oriented war still dominated across all three communities. TABLE 1. GROUPS AND PARTI CIPATI ON IN DEFE NSIVE WARS (PER CE NT) MY PE OPLE HAVE FOUGHT ONLY DEFENSIVE WARS (2005) NATI ONAL BE LONGING BOSNI AK CROAT SERB TOTAL Totally agree 85.3 75.9 76.2 79.4 Somewhat agree 11.7 16.6 16.8 14.9 Somewhat disagree 1.8 2.9 4.1 2.9 Totally disagree .2 .5 .4 .4 Don’t know 1.0 4.1 2.6 2.5 MY PE OPLE HAVE FOUGHT ONLY DEFENSIVE WARS (2010) NATI ONAL BE LONGING BOSNI AK CROAT SERB TOTAL Totally agree 81 70 54.7 68.6 Somewhat agree 16.6 24.5 33.5 24.8 Somewhat disagree 0.5 2.7 5.8 3 Totally disagree 0.3 0.8 0.2 0 Don’t know 1.0 2 5.8 2.9 The differences based on ethnic belonging are also fairly strong when the respondents are asked to define the character of the war in Bosnia and Herzegovina. It is apparent from the findings that there has been almost no change in the predominant ethno-national definitions of the war in Bosnia and Herzegovina. In 2010, 87.4 per cent of Serbs characterised the conflict as a civil war, while 96.6 per cent Bosniaks and 69.6 per cent Croats considered it to be an act of aggression on 656 SOCIOLOGIJA, Vol. LIV (2012), N° 4 Bosnia and Herzegovina. The complexity of the overall view of the past is particularly vivid when the interviewees were asked to name the military force(s) which, according to them, could be characterised as playing the role of defender in the recent war. TABLE 2. DEFINITI ON OF WAR IN BOSNI A AND HERZE GOVI NA (PE R CE NT) IN YOUR VIE W, WHI CH OF T HESE I S T HE BEST DEFINITI ON OF T HE LAST WAR IN BOSNI A AND HERZE GOVINA? (2005) NATI ONAL BE LONGING BOSNI AK CROAT SERB TOTAL Civil war 3.7 16.7 83.6 34.2 Aggression 95.1 73.2 9.0 59.8 Don’t know 1.2 10.1 7.4 6.0 IN YOUR VIE W, WHI CH OF T HESE I S T HE BEST DEFINITI ON OF T HE LAST WAR IN BOSNI A AND HERZE GOVINA? (2010) NATI ONAL BE LONGING BOSNI AK CROAT SERB TOTAL Civil war 2.7 28.3 87.3 39.4 Aggression 96.6 69.6 9 58.4 Don’t know 0.6 2.1 3.7 2.2 TABLE 3. WAR IN BOSNI A AND HERZE GOVI NA AND DE FINITI ON OF DEFENDERS (PE R CENT) PLEASE TELL US, ACCORDING TO YOU, WHICH OF THESE MILITARY FORCES CAN BE BEST CHARACTERISED AS DEFENDERS IN THE LAST WAR? (2005) NATI ONAL BE LONGING BOSNI AK CROAT SERB TOTAL HVO 5.9 92.7 1.8 31.0 Armija BiH 91.4 1.2 1.2 34.0 Vojska RS .1 .1 89.6 29.8 Vojska AP Zapadne Bosne .6 .0 .0 .2 JNA .0 .3 4.5 1.6 Don’t know 2.0 5.7 2.9 3.4 PLEASE TELL US, ACCORDING TO YOU, WHICH OF THESE MILITARY FORCES CAN BE BEST CHARACTERISED AS DEFENDERS IN THE LAST WAR? (2010) NATI ONAL BE LONGING BOSNI AK CROAT SERB TOTAL HVO 5.9 92.1 1.6 33.2 Armija BiH 91.2 6.6 2 33.2 Vojska RS .9 .6 88 29.8 Vojska AP Zapadne Bosne 1.5 .0 .6 .7 JNA .3 .4 6.8 2.5 Don’t know .2 .2 1 .5 When asked this question in 2005, a majority of the Croat respondents, 92.7 per cent, saw the Croat Defence Council (HVO) as defenders. Most Bosniaks, 91.4 Roland Kostić: Transitional Justice and Reconciliation in Bosnia-Herzegovina... 657 per cent, named the Army of Bosnia and Herzegovina (Armija BiH) as the defending force, while 89.6 per cent of the Serbs stated that the Army RS (Vojska RS) was the defender. Only 5.9 per cent of Bosniaks regard the HVO as defenders, while 4.5 per cent of Serbs primarily saw the Yugoslav Peoples Army (JNA) in this context. In the 2010 survey there was almost no change in the prevailing ethno- national perceptions that dominate popular opinion among the three groups in Bosnia and Herzegovina. Overall, the empirical findings clearly indicate that the members of the three ethno-national communities in Bosnia and Herzegovina maintain diverging perspectives on and memories of wartime events and actors. The vast majority of all the respondent groups share the view that their people had been fighting a defensive war. However, while a majority of Bosniaks and Croats tend to characterise the recent war as aggression, most Serbs see it as a civil war. Finally, when asked to name a defending military force, most Croats chose the Croat Defence Council, a majority of the Bosniaks the Army of Bosnia and Herzegovina and most Serbs the Army RS. The data presented above show vividly that, at present, there is hardly any common understanding of the past between the ethno-national communities in Bosnia and Herzegovina, and that the great majority of the members of each group continue to subscribe to mutually exclusive ethno-national narratives. Different mechanisms for promoting reconciliation in Bosnia and Herzegovina Retributive justice Delivering justice to victims is seen as a precondition for reconciliation. Justice has many faces, however, and retributive justice is one of them. The notion of retributive justice rests on the idea that war crimes and crimes against humanity require accountability and prosecution, since such actions threaten both the domestic and the international order. The idea behind retributive justice is that it reduces the risk of revenge, prevents a return to power by the perpetrators of war crimes and crimes against humanity, and leads to the individualisation of accountability, thereby removing the stigma of collective guilt from whole communities. Furthermore, by publicly acknowledging who was right and who was wrong, restorative justice can help to heal wounds and restore the self-confidence of most victims. Finally, trials may provide additional information to fill the gaps in knowledge about the past. This rationale has been obvious in the creation of the ad hoc International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia and of the War Crimes Chamber of the State Court of Bosnia and Herzegovina. 658 SOCIOLOGIJA, Vol. LIV (2012), N° 4 The International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia The International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia was established by United Nations Security Council Resolution 827 of 25 May 1993. Its purpose was to prosecute the persons responsible for the serious violations of international humanitarian law committed on the territory of the former Yugoslavia after 1 January 1991. The inclusion of the ICTY in the Dayton Peace Accords was envisaged as part of the external effort to promote justice and reconciliation in Bosnia and Herzegovina. Bosniak, Croat and Serb leaders committed themselves to cooperate with the ICTY in its efforts to deliver a more comprehensive narrative on wartime events and bring about a sense of justice for the victims. Initially, the ICTY prosecuted local perpetrators of war crimes in order to establish evidence to link senior military and political commanders to such events. However, its limited time and resources, and the large number of people to be indicted, led to a change in strategy. Senior military commanders and political leaders were indicted and prosecuted from all three communities in Bosnia and Herzegovina as well as the rest of the former Yugoslavia. Altogether, 161 persons were indicted by the ICTY. Proceedings have been completed in 126 cases, while 35 persons still await their final hearing. There have been 73 guilty verdicts, 5 people have been acquitted, 13 cases have been transferred to the local courts and 35 cases have been stopped, either because the indictment was withdrawn or because the accused died. In one of its most high-profile findings, the ICTY ruled that the massacre in Srebrenica perpetrated by the Bosnian Serb forces was a case of local genocide against Bosniaks in Srebrenica. However, the popular attitudes towards the ICTY trials noted in the 2010 survey show only a limited short-term impact on reconciliation, or delivering a narrative about the past and a sense of justice to victims. While 74.3 per cent of the Bosniaks, and 61.2 per cent of the Croats somewhat or totally agree that the work of the ICTY is precondition for just peace and coexistence, only 15.2 per cent of the Serb respondents somewhat or totally agree with this view. In addition, while 56.7 per cent of the Bosniaks somewhat or totally agree that the trials at the ICTY are fair, 56.6 per cent of Croat and 89.6 per cent of Serbs in BiH somewhat or totally disagree with this view. Furthermore, the attitude changes regarding the work of ICTY and its fairness between 2005 and 2010 are minimal. These findings are not surprising, given the presence of three conflicting group narratives about the war and its causes. In addition, it is impossible to control the existence of selective hearing among ordinary people, that is, the tendency for individuals to express an interest in the trials dealing with crimes against members of their own group, while ignoring the trials in which individuals belonging to their groups are prosecuted for war crimes. Such tendencies may lead to a confirmation of existing narratives. Roland Kostić: Transitional Justice and Reconciliation in Bosnia-Herzegovina... 659 TABLE 4. PERCEPTI ONS OF T HE ICTY IN 2005 (PE R CENT) TO WHAT EXTENT DO YOU AGREE WIT H T HE FOLLOWING STATE MENT S? NATI ONAL BE LONGING BOSNI AK CROAT SERB TOTAL The war crimes tribunal in The Hague is a precondition for a just peace and normal relations Totally agree 51.6 18.7 4.7 26.0 Somewhat agree 28.7 38.4 11.1 25.8 Somewhat disagree 5.1 11.0 15.4 10.3 Totally disagree 11.0 27.7 63.3 33.5 Don’t know 3.7 4.2 5.5 4.4 The trials at the Tribunal are fair Totally agree 32.7 11.3 4.3 16.7 Somewhat agree 35.2 31.9 9.2 25.6 Somewhat disagree 9.3 15.2 11.2 11.7 Totally disagree 19.8 36.7 68.0 41.0 Don’t know 3.0 4.9 7.3 5.0 TABLE 5. PERCEPTI ONS OF T HE ICTY IN 2010 (PE R CENT) TO WHAT EXTENT DO YOU AGREE WIT H T HE FOLLOWING STATE MENT S? NATI ONAL BE LONGING BOSNI AK CROAT SERB TOTAL The war crimes tribunal in The Hague is a precondition for a just peace and normal relations Totally agree 45.5 22.9 3.2 23.8 Somewhat agree 28.8 38.3 12.0 26.3 Somewhat disagree 10.3 19.5 24.6 18.1 Totally disagree 11.7 16.5 58.7 29 Don’t know 3.6 2.8 1.5 2.7 The trials at the Tribunal are fair Totally agree 24.8 10.9 4.0 13.2 Somewhat agree 31.9 29.2 5.2 22.1 Somewhat disagree 15.1 22.9 22.0 20.0 Totally disagree 24.0 33.7 67.6 41.7 Don’t know 4.2 3.3 1.2 2.9 With this in mind, the fact that Bosnian Serb political leaders and politicians have been tried and sentenced in the greatest number, followed by Bosnian Croats, probably explains why both Serbs and Croats in Bosnia and Herzegovina are sceptical about the processes and fairness of the ICTY (see Kostić 2007: 269–272).7 Nonetheless, given that the trials will not be completed until the end of 2014, and the process of reconciliation takes time, an understanding of the ICTY’s contribution to justice and reconciliation in Bosnia and Herzegovina will only become clear in the future. ———— 7 The positive perception of the ICTY has been greatly undermined by numerous controversies in relation to the trials or lack of thereof. As noted, prosecution of heads of states from the regions gave mixed results. Milošević died during the trial, while in the case of Alija Izetbegović and Franjo Tudjman ICTY issued general statements after their deaths that both would have been indicted if they have lived longer. Furthermore, the prosecution against Kosovo Albanian guerilla leader Ramush Haradinaj failed partly due to intimidation of key witnesses (Dragović-Soso and Gordy 2011: 190). 660 SOCIOLOGIJA, Vol. LIV (2012), N° 4 The War Crimes Chamber of the State Court of Bosnia-Herzegovina Since the ICTY has been unable to process all the war crimes suspects from Bosnia and Herzegovina during its time-limited period of operation, the Parliament of Bosnia and Herzegovina, acting on a law promulgated by the OHR in 2000, established the State Court of Bosnia and Herzegovina, and its War Crimes Chamber, in July 2002. The State Court of Bosnia and Herzegovina is a hybrid tribunal, since it is under national jurisdiction but employs both international and domestic judges (48 domestic and five international). In addition, it applies a mixture of international and domestic law in processing accusations of war crimes and human rights abuses. It was believed that the establishment of the State Court of Bosnia and Herzegovina would deliver justice regarding events that were not covered by the ICTY, cut the cost of the process and bring the proceedings closer to the affected population, thereby increasing ownership of the process. Since 2002, the Chamber has passed 93 sentences for war crimes and human rights abuses. Currently, 67 people have been indicted, linked to 32 unresolved cases of war crimes (OSCE 2011). Trials are expected to last for decades since the list of suspects contains some 10 000 names. Although the War Crimes Chamber has been in place for almost a decade, it is difficult to draw definite conclusion about its impact on justice and reconciliation in Bosnia and Herzegovina. The survey data from 2010 show that many in Bosnia and Herzegovina seldom follow the work of the War Crimes Chamber. Only 60 per cent of Bosnian Croat and 75 per cent of Bosnian Serb respondents followed the work of the Chamber either once or a few times a year. Even among Bosniaks, 52 per cent tended to follow the trials only once or a few times a year. TABLE 6. PERCEPTI ONS OF T HE BOSNI A AND HE RZE GOVINA WAR CRIME S TRIBUNAL IN 2010 (PE R CENT) TO WHAT EXTENT DO YOU AGREE WIT H T HE FOLLOWING STATE MENT S? NATI ONAL BE LONGING BOSNI AK CROAT SERB TOTAL The work of war crimeschamber of the BiH Court is a precondition for a just peace and normal relations Totally agree 44.1 27.5 5.2 25.6 Somewhat agree 34.2 31.6 16.6 27.4 Somewhat disagree 7.8 18.8 28.3 18.4 Totally disagree 5.4 15.9 40 20.4 Don’t know 8.5 6.2 9.9 8.2 The trials in the War Crimes Chamber of the BiH Court are fair Totally agree 29.7 7 2.2 12.9 Somewhat agree 43.2 27.6 9.4 26.7 Somewhat disagree 9.9 26.5 25.9 20.8 Totally disagree 8.3 32.3 52.7 31.2 Don’t know 8.9 6.6 9.8 8.4 Roland Kostić: Transitional Justice and Reconciliation in Bosnia-Herzegovina... 661 While 78.3 per cent of the Bosniak and 59.1 per cent of the Croat respondents either somewhat or totally agreed that the work of the War Crimes Chamber was a precondition for a just peace and coexistence, only 21.8 per cent of the Serb respondents either somewhat or totally agreed with this view. In addition, while 72.9 per cent of the Bosniaks viewed the trials at the War Crimes Chamber as fair, 78.6 per cent of the Serb and 52 per cent of the Croat respondents disagreed with this view. These data on attitudes to the War Crimes Chamber demonstrate the difficulties in delivering justice and accountability for war crimes in highly divided societies. First, the War Crimes Chamber lacks the capacity to deal with a large number of crimes, and until now only a small percentage of perpetrators have been prosecuted, which may have contributed to the perception of its arbitrariness. Second, considering the prevalence of three selective collective narratives about the war, and their impact on the social climate in Bosnia and Herzegovina, it is difficult to produce measured and fair punishment for individual war criminals without this being interpreted in terms of the responsibility and guilt of whole communities. There is also a substantial degree of political pressure from all sides, in an attempt to influence the investigations, trials and verdicts of the War Crimes Chamber.8 Finally, the Bosnian case also testifies to the general limitations of tribunals in swiftly altering established selective group narratives about war and promoting true or more nuanced perspectives on wartime events. The truth about the war in Bosnia and Herzegovina Truth is not a replacement for judicial trials. However, establishing the truth about past events is a very important element in the process of national and political reconciliation. The most common mechanism for truth seeking is national truth commissions. An alternative is truth finding commissions about specific war-time events. In addition, non-governmental projects are promoted in some instances to document abuses and human rights violations. Swedish International Development and Cooperation Agency (Sida) and the United State Institute of Peace (USIP), together with a local NGO, Truth and Reconciliation, argued for the establishment of a truth commission for Bosnia and Herzegovina. According to the survey data from 2010, 85 per cent of the Bosniaks, 83 per cent of the Croats, and 65 per cent of Serb respondents agree that it would be good for peace to form a truth commission. The initiative never materialised. The external supervisors of the peace process in BiH feared that such an initiative would draw away financial resources from the ICTY and would also compromise on-going processes at the tribunal (Dragović- Soso and Gordy, 2011; Dragović-Soso, 2012). This was coupled with absence of the domestic political will to support such an initiative, but also due to a lack of interest ———— 8 Interview with a prosecutor working at the War Crimes Chamber in Sarajevo, 13 October 2011. 662 SOCIOLOGIJA, Vol. LIV (2012), N° 4 from the victims’ associations (Dragović-Soso and Gordy, 2011). At the same time, there has been little political will to acknowledge the crimes committed by members of one’s own community or to apologise for such crimes. The Srebrenica Commission In order to establish the truth about the events in Srebrenica in the summer of 1995, and to increase awareness among the population of Republika Srpska of these events, in 2003 the OHR forced the Assembly of Republika Srpska to establish the Commission for Investigation of the Events in and around Srebrenica between 10 and 19 July 1995 (Dragović-Soso and Gordy, 2011: 204). Its final report was published in 2004. The Srebrenica Commission collected a significant amount of new information. It established that on 10–19 July1995, 7800 Bosniak men and boys were executed by the forces of the Republika Srpska Army. The Commission also described how the perpetrators moved the bodies to secondary graves in order to cover up their crimes. Guided by information from sources in Republika Srpska, the Commission was able to discover 32 gravesites. Finally, it established the structure of the military forces participating in the massacres, and created an identity database of those who perished in the massacres (The Commission for Srebrenica, 2004). The work of the Commission resulted in an official apology by the Government of Republika Srpska to the Bosniaks of Srebrenica on 10 November 2004 (Associated Press, 2004). In its apology, the Government of Republika Srpska acknowledged that a massive crime had taken place during the Republika Srpska Army offensive on Srebrenica in 1995, and expressed its readiness to face up to the tragic events of the war in Bosnia and Herzegovina. At the same time, the RS President Dragan Čavić insisted that there was no basis to speak of genocide in Srebrenica (Dragović- Soso and Gordy 2011: 205). A majority of the population in both Republika Srpska and Bosnia and Herzegovina are now familiar with the events in Srebrenica. According to the survey data from 2010, some 97 per cent of the Bosniaks, Serbs and Croats interviewed had heard about the events there. While 97.8 per cent of Bosniak and 96 Croat respondents considered these to be war crimes, this view was shared by only 55.7 per cent of the Serb interviewees. Among Serb respondents, 16.2 per cent did not know how to characterise the events, and 24.2 per cent viewed them as an unfortunate consequence of military operations. Regarding the apology by the Government of Republika Srpska, 36.8 per cent of the Bosniak respondents believed that it came under pressure from the international community, while 33 per cent believed it relevant to telling the truth about war crimes but not for reconciliation. By contrast, 35.3 per cent of Bosnian Croat interviewees considered the apology an important step towards inter-ethnic reconciliation, while 30.6 per cent believed that it came as a result of pressure from the international community. Among Bosnian Serb respondents, 27.3 per cent viewed it as an important step for inter-ethnic Roland Kostić: Transitional Justice and Reconciliation in Bosnia-Herzegovina... 663 reconciliation, 20.3 pre cent viewed it as important for truth about the events but nor for reconciliation, 20.6 per cent saw it as a result of international pressure, 21.4 per cent had not heard about it and 10.3 per cent did not have an opinion. It is important to note that despite the apology and the acknowledgement of the Srebrenica killings, leading Bosnian Serb politicians continue to object to its legal categorisation by the ICTY as a local genocide, and see this as an attempt to stigmatise the Serb population of Bosnia and Herzegovina and delegitimise Republika Srpska (Marić, 2010; Flego, 2012). The Research and Documentation Centre in Sarajevo and truth-seeking about the casualties of war Since April 2004, the internationally sponsored Research and Documentation Centre (RDC) in Sarajevo has been leading an additional and significant truth- finding initiative about the war in Bosnia and Herzegovina. The guiding ideas behind the centre are to establish and publish facts about the war, promote the truth in order to prevent selective manipulation of events, assist the judiciary in prosecuting suspected war criminals and strengthen civil society. Until 2009, the RDC also participated in the regional network of “civil society” organisations working to create a regional commission (RECOM) that aimed to establish the facts about the victims of all war crimes and other serious human rights violations committed on the territory of the former Yugoslavia during the wars of Yugoslav succession (Bilić, 2011: 305). The RDC has collected some one million documents, 60,000 photographs and 3500 hours of video material. It has made its findings available online, and organised numerous public lectures all over Bosnia and Herzegovina. Its work has led to a revision of previously quoted figures for the dead or missing as a result of the war. According to an RDC report, The Bosnian Book of the Dead, 97,207 died or are missing as a result of the war: Bosniaks lost 33,070 civilians and 30,966 soldiers; Croat losses were 2163 civilians and 5625 soldiers; and, according to the RDC, 4075 Serb civilians and 20,830 Serb soldiers died as a result of the war. Given the substantial number of missing persons, RDC experts anticipate that the final total figure may increase by another 10,000. The findings of the RDC have been independently confirmed by work by the Demographic Unit of the ICTY, which produced a similar figure of 104,732 dead during the war in Bosnia and Herzegovina. However, even these findings have been challenged and interpreted differently in different parts of Bosnia and Herzegovina. A recent survey from 2011 shows that 20 per cent of respondents agreed that the death toll was 100 000 or less, 32 per cent believed that the final figure will never be established, while some 48 per cent believed in the previously cited figure of 200,000 or more dead as a result of the war. Interestingly, in the Bosniak dominated Sarajevo 60 per cent of the respondents believed that 200,000 or more had died as a result of the war, while in 664 SOCIOLOGIJA, Vol. LIV (2012), N° 4 the Serb dominated Banja Luka 70 per cent agreed with the figure of 100 000 or fewer dead (Dnevni Avaz, 2011). Conclusions The war in Bosnia-Herzegovina was one of the bloodiest episodes since 1945. It had an immense impact on individuals, inter-group relations and society at large. However, the Bosnian case shows that when dealing with the consequences of mass violence, it is important to consider how the politics of external state-building affects reconciliation and what can be achieved by transitional justice initiatives. As is show in this paper, the outcomes of the various transitional justice initiatives tested in Bosnia and Herzegovina have been interpreted primarily from the fragmented perspectives of the three salient collective narratives. Thus, until now, the various measures have had only limited effects on promoting a common understanding of the past and a sense that justice has been done. Given that more than 18 years has passed since the beginning of DPA implementation, the question arises whether the intrusive external strategies of comprehensive political, economic, legal and institutional regulation that have been tested in Bosnia and Herzegovina have been able to achieve anything more than a no war, no peace situation. The prevalence of external neoliberal practices of regulation in political and economic life in Bosnia and Herzegovina has resulted in peace-building without politics. In a situation in which domestic politics about the organization of society and its future are not feasible, discussion about the past becomes the inherent arena for politics. By maintaining opposing narratives about past events, the members of the main three BiH communities have developed a way of legitimizing their own positions in response to claims by other communities and to the external regulation of domestic state-building processes. This in essence transforms the debate over the recent conflict from a transitional process of coming to terms with the past to a permanent state of affairs. The process, as seen in Bosnia and Herzegovina, precludes reconciliation in terms of mutual acknowledgment of suffering and a nuanced understanding of the causes and dynamics of the violent conflict. Finally, the Bosnian case shows that the meaning of reconciliation is not universal and often has specific cultural and political aspects. Therefore, before promoting various reconciliatory initiatives, it would be useful to establish what is to be reconciled and who are the actors in the process. The case of Bosnia and Herzegovina demonstrates that reconciliation has much to do with past communal claims and grievances, and their relation to current politics. This means that promoting reconciliation goes hand in hand with finding durable political solutions to existing incompatibilities. In consequence, this means that supporting a durable, locally produced and owned political settlement would remove a major obstacle to reconciliation among the populations and elites of Bosnia and Herzegovina. Roland Kostić: Transitional Justice and Reconciliation in Bosnia-Herzegovina... 665 References Bar-Tal, Daniel. 2007. “Sociopsychological Foundations of Intractable Conflicts”, American Behavioral Scientist, vol. 50, no. 11: 1430-1453. Bar-Tal, Daniel. 2000. Shared Beliefs in a Society- Social Psychological Analysis. Thousand Oaks, London, New Delhi: Sage Publications. Bilić, Bojan. 2011. “A Concept that is Everything and Nothing: Why not to Study (Post-) Yugoslav Anti-War and Pacifist Contention from a Civil Society Perspective“. Sociologija. vol. LIII, no. 3: 297- 322. Borer, Anne Tristan. 2006. “Truth Telling as a Peace-Building Activity: A Theoretical Overview”, in Tristan, Anne Borer (ed). Telling the Truths: Truth Telling and Peace Building in Post-Conflict Societies. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. “Bosnian Serbs issue apology for massacre”. Associated Press, Banja Luka, 11 November 2004.accessed on www.bosnia.org.uk on 24 May 2012. Chandler, David. 2005. “Introduction: Peace without Politics?”. International Peacekeeping, vol. 12, no. 3: 307 – 321. Devine-Wright, P. 2003. “A theoretical overview of memory and conflict”. In Cairns, E. and Roe, M.D. (Ed.), The role of memory in ethnic conflict. New York: Palgrave Macmillan. Dragović-Soso, Jasna and Gordy, Eric. 2010. “Coming to Terms with the Past. Transitional Justice and Reconciliation in the post-Yugoslav lands”. In Djoković, Dejan and Ker- Lindsay, James (ed) New Perspectives on Yugoslavia. Routledge. Dragović-Soso, Jasna. 2012. “Autopsy of a Failure: Attempts to Create a Truth and Reconciliation Commission in Bosnia and Herzegovina”. Paper presented at NEMMA Aarhus Workshop, “Twenty Years of Memory: Prosecuting, Memorializing and Remembering the Wars of Yugoslav Succession”. 30-31 January, Aarhus University, Denmark. E.D.A. 2011. „Manje od pola građana vjeruje da je u agresiji bilo 200 hiljada ili više žrtava”, Dnevni Avaz, 10 April. Sarajevo. Eriksson, Mikael and Kostić, Roland. 2013 (forthcoming). Mediation and Liberal Peace building: Peace from the Ashes of War?, London and New York: Routledge. EU Presidency Statement – Post-Conflict National Reconciliation – The Role of the United Nations. Statement to the Security Council of the United Nations by H.E. Ambassador Richard Ryan. Permanent Representative of Ireland to the UN on behalf of the European Union. (New York), January 26, 2004. Flego, Miroslav. 2012. „Dodik: Nikolić je u pravu, u Srebrenici nije bilo genocide”. Večernji list. Zagreb. 09 June 2012. Accessed on http://www.vecernji.hr/vijesti/dodik-nikolic-je- pravu-srebrenici-nije-bilo-genocida-clanak-418114 on 10 June 2012. Krampe, Florian. “The Liberal Trap - Peacemaking and Peacebuilding in Afghanistan after 9/11. 2013”. In Eriksson, Mikael and Kostić, Roland (ed) Mediation and Liberal Peace building: Peace from the Ashes of War?. London and New York: Routledge. Galtung, Johan. 2012. Peace by Peaceful Means- Peace and Conflict, Development and Civilisation, Los Angeles, London, New Delhi, Singapore, Washington, Sage Publications. Hayden, Robert. 2005. “Democracy without a demos? The Bosnian constitutional experiment and the intentional construction of nonfunctioning states”. East European politics and societies, vol. 19, no. 2: 226- 259. 666 SOCIOLOGIJA, Vol. LIV (2012), N° 4 Hayner, Priscilla B. 2001. Unspeakable Truths: Confronting State Terror and Atrocities. New York: Routledge. Huyse, Luc. 2005. “The Process of Reconciliation", in Bloomfield, Barns, David Teresa and Huyse, Luc (ed) Reconciliation after Violent Conflict – a Handbook, Stockholm: IDEA. Jeong, Ho-Won. 2005. Peacebuilding in Postconflict Societies: Strategies and Processes. London and Boulder: Lynne Rienner Publishers. Kostić, Roland. 2007. Ambivalent Peace: External Nation-building, Threatened Identity and Reconciliation in Bosnia-Herzegovina. PhD dissertation. Departmentof Peace and Conflict Research. Uppsala University. (pp. 421). Kostić, Roland. 2008. “Nation-Building as an Instrument of Peace? Exploring Local Attitudes Towards International Nation-Building Building and Reconciliation in Bosnia and Herzegovina”. Civil Wars, vol.10, no. 4: 386-414. Kostić, Roland. 2011. “Education through Regulation- External intervention in domestic politics in post-Dayton Bosnia and Herzegovina”. In Fjelde, Hanne and Höglund, Kristine (ed) Building Peace, Creating Conflict? Conflictual Dimensions of Local and International Peacebuilding. Lund: Nordic Academic Press. Lederach, John Paul. 1997. Building Peace: Sustainable Reconciliation in Divided Societies, Washington D.C.: USIP Marić, Boro. 2010. “Dodik: Zločin ne negiramo, tražimoistinu”. Politika. Beograd. issue of 20 April. Accessed on http://www.politika.rs/rubrike/region/Dodik-Zlochin-ne-negiramo- trazimo-istinu.lt.html on 25 May 2012. Nystuen, Gro. 2005. Achieveing Peace or Protecting Human Rights?: Conflict Between Norms Regarding Ethnic Discrimination in the Dayton Peace Agreement Leiden, NDL: Matinus Nijhoff Publishers. O'Brien, James. C. 2005. ”The Dayton Agreement in Bosnia: Durable Cease-Fire, Permanent Negotiations”. In: Zartman William & Kremenyuk Victor (ed.) Peace versus Justice: Negotiationg Forward- and Backward-Looking Outcomes. Lanham, Boulder, New York, Toronto, Oxford: Rowman& Littlefield Publishers. Rigby, Andrew. 2001. Justice and Reconciliation: After the Violence. Boulder, Colorado: Lynne Rienner Publishers. Serwer, Daniel. “Towards Reconciliation: A New Vision for the OSCE?”, paper presented at Session IV, OSCE Security Days, Vienna, 23-24 June 2012. Sriram, Chandra Lekha. 2009. “Justice as Peace? Liberal Peacebuilding and Strategies of Transitional justice”. Mac Ginty, Roger and Richmond, Oliver. (ed) The Liberal Peace and Post-War Reconstruction- Myth or Reality. New York and Oxon: Routledge. Subotić, Jelena. 2009. Hijacked justice: dealing with the past in the Balkans. Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press. The Commission for Investigation of the Events in and Around Srebrenica Between 10th and 19the July 1995.Events in and Around Srebrenica Between 10th and 19th July 1995.RepublikaSrpska Government. Bosnia and Herzegovina. Banja Luka. 2004. Vinjamuri, Leslie and Boesenecker, Aron. 2007. Accountability and Peace Agreements Mapping trends from 1980 to 2006. Birmingham: Centre for Humanitarian Dialogue. 1- 56. Wallensteen, Peter. 2012. Understanding Conflict Resolution, 3rd edition, London: Sage. Williams. Paul R. and Scharf, Michael P. 2002. Peace with Justice? War Crimes and Accountability in the Former Yugoslavia. Lanham, Boulder, New York, Oxford: Rowman& Littlefield Publishers. work_34gmhf2s6ngnxda44hmy6uwdoq ---- '" REAFFIRMING REHABILITATION IN JUVENILE JUSTICE Dan Macallair, M.P.A Center on Juvenile and Criminal Justice San Francisco, CA Paper presented at the annual meetings of the Western Society of Criminology Berkeley, CA February 1991 Abstract This article examines the decline of rehabilitation in juvenile justice throughout much of the United States over the past 20 years. This decline was facilitated by the progressive community's abandonment of rehabilitation and their acceptance of the justice model as a means to restrict the growing number of youth in correctional institutions. The justice model was conceived as a means to impose confinement limitations through standardized sentencing, while accommodating conservative demands for retribution and punishment. However, contrary to expe<:tations, the justice model promoted an unprecedented rise in the number of incarcerated youth and a deterioration in institutional conditions. This was occurring despite mounting evidence demonstrating the superior effectiveness of rehabilitation models in altering patterns of delinquency. Conclusions were based on an analysis of juvenile correctional systems in California, Massachusetts, Utah, Washington. The evidence shows that rehabilitation should be reaffirmed as the foundation for a progressive agenda in juvenile justice. REAFFIRMING REHABILITATION IN JUVENILE JUSTICE TABLE OF CONTENTS Rehabilitation and the Juvenile Justice System Diversion and Deinstitutionalization The Ascendancy of the Justice Model The Impact of the Justice Model on Juvenile Correctional Systems Rehabilitation and Organizational Commitment Comparing Rehabilitation Models with Justice Models Reconsidering Rehabilitation Conclusion Graphs References I 2 3 4 6 8 9 12 Rehabilitation and the Juvenile Justice System For the past 20 years, the juvenile justice system in the United States has been the subject of the most intensive policy debates in its history. These debates were the result of a number of studies conducted during the 1970s which concluded that most correctional rehabilitation programs had little impact on the offender's post-release behavior. The most infamous of these studies was the Lipton, Martinson, and Wilks (1975) report. After examining 231 evaluation studies of correctional treatment programs, the authors concluded, "with few and isolated exceptions, the rehabilitative efforts that have been reported so fur have no appreciable effect on recidivism (1975, p.25): This statement, interpreted as "nothing works," resounded throughout correctional . bureaucracies, legislatures, and the media. The Lipton, Martinson, and Wilks report" was . published at a time when crime rates were on the rise (Krisberg, Schwartz, Litsky, Austin, 1986). Many viewed this trend as indicative of a breakdown in the moral and social order and the leniency of the criminal courts. The indictment of the rehabilitative model, along with growing public concern over crime, propelled a search for an alternative. Conservatives traditionally viewed the philosophy of rehabilitation with derision, because it cont1icted with their notion of deterrence and reciprocity through punishment. Liberals, lamenting the juvenile justice system'S historic emphasis on custody and control, abandoned their traditional support for rehabilitation as impractical. As a result of this dissension, rehabilitation experienced a precipitous decline throughout most of the United States during the 1980s (Greenwood 1986). The concept of rehabilitation in juvenile justice was based on the belief that childhood and adolescence are periods of growth and development. Since patterns of proper behavior evolve from nurturing, the goal of benign intervention was to serve the best interests of the child. With the state assuming the role of parent, formal legal procedures and protections were shunned in favor of an informal decision process (Empey 1982). For most of the 19th and 20th centuries, youths under the age of 18 were sent to institutions, also known as reform schools or training schools, for offenses such as stubbornness, thievery, truancy, assault, and lewdness. The institution's purpose was to provide a strict and isolated environment far from urban corruption where youths could be imbued with proper work habits and moral fortitude (Empey 1982). However, it was soon recognized that involuntary confinement in these instj.tutions bred the worst aspects of human behavior. As a result, staff became obsessed with maintaining Center on Juvenile and Criminal Justice • 1622 Folsom Street· San Francisco, California 94103 Page 2 order and security. As living conditions grew more restrictive and oppressive, youths became more recalcitrant and the institutional environment became the antithesis of humane .individualized care (Rothman 1980). After reviewing the history of the Massachusetts State Reform School at Westborough, Lief (1988, p.1) noted that despite continual attempts to "reconstruct architecture, secularize tbe curriculum, revise the roles of personnel, rename · philosophical objectives, and modify systems of punishment and contro1...it is striking how little the daily experiences of inmates and keepers changed over a period of 128 years." Under the institutional system, the goal of rehabilitation became subordinate to organizational demands and political expediency. Policy makers, needing a convenient response to crime and poverty issues, continued to expand the number of public training schools throughout the 19th and 20th centuries. By 1960, the position of institutions as the foundation for the juvenile correctional system stood unchallenged. Diversion and Deinstitutionalization During the 1960s, the efficacy of correctional institutions came under increasing assault (President's Commission on Law Enforcement and Administration of Justice, 1967). In response, reformers designed new strategies to reduce the number of institutionalized youth. Two primary reforms emerged from these efforts: diversion and deinstitutionalization. , Diversion was designed to encourage police, prosecutors, and probation officers to refer youths to community programs as an alternative to arrest and formal judicial processing. However, later evaluations revealed that diversion was practiced on youths who previously ... : would have been released at the time of intake and not formally processed (Klein 1975). In . -. addition, youths who were not deemed eligible for diversion were subjected to harsher · treatment and more severe sanctions (Palmer 1978). This situation led researchers to conclude · that diversion was actually extending systems of social control (Krisberg and Austin, 1981). Deinstitutionalization was intended to divert youths from correctional institutions once they were formally processed and committed. One of the most widely reviewed experiments of deinstitutionalization was carried out by the California Youth Authority (CY A) during the 1960s .. In an effort to slow its institutional population growth, the CY A, through state legislation, initiated a probation subsidy program to encourage counties to retain youths at the loca1leve!. While its purpose was to reduce commitments to the state juvenile correctional system, it was never intended to replace or supplant the CY A's institutional system. Later . studies revealed that throughout the period of probation subsidy, institutional expansion in California continued. Although the rate of commitments declined, periods of confinement Center on Juvenile and Criminal Justice' 1622 Folsom Street· San Francisco, California 94103 Page 3 within CY A institutions were steadily increased to maintain a consistent population. In addition, counties began expanding local training schools and secure detention facilities. The proportion of institutionalized youths throughout California remained unchanged during the period of probation subsidy (Lerman 1975). The Ascendancy of the Justice Model Disillusioned with the failed efforts of diversion and deinstitutionalization, progressive reformers sought to reconcile their strategies to the institutional system' s realities. To reach a compromise with conservative constituencies, many juvenile justice reformers embraced the justice or "just deserts" model of corrections (Cullen and Gilbert 1984; Castellano, 1986). First promulgated in the 1970s, the justice model is founded on the concept of fixed and uniform degrees of punishment for specific crimes. Its intent is to inject certainty and consistency into the sentencing process by limiting the discretion of judges and correctional personnel in determining lengths of incarceration. Under this scheme, correctional administrators are no longer expected to pursue rehabilitation or other forms of individualized intervention. Their main function is to administer punishments in a fair and humane manner (Fogel 1975). Contrary to the expectations of its proponents, the justice model strengthened the institutional system and left progressive advocates without a compelling alternative. In their critique of the justice model, researchers Cullen and Gilbert (1981, pp. 19-20) identified three primary failures of this strategy as a basis for progressive reform: First, in basing punishment strictly on the crime and not the criminal, implicit in the determinate sentencing paradigm is the assumption that the state not only has no right but also no obligation to do anything about the condition or needs of an offender. Yet, we may ask, is a philosophy that gives legitimacy to state neglect of individual needs likely to be more benevolent than one that mandates, however imperfectly, state concern? Second, it is highly ironic that those who mistrust the state to administer criminal justice rehabilitation in a just and humane manner are now placing their total faith in the state (the legislature in particular) to punish justly and humanely. We have searched in vain to discover the basis for this faith. And third, in the past, the failure of treatment programs has invariably evoked a plea among liberal reformers that inmates receive more and not less rehabilitation. When the new agenda for punishment fails to reduce crime at some point in the future, what will the call be for then? Less punishment - or more? Center on Juvenile and Criminal Justice • 1622 Folsom Street • San Francisco, California 94103 --j. Page 4 The reality of Cullen and Gilbert's warnings was quickly manifested. The justice model facilitated unprecedented increases in institutional populations and an accompanying deterioration in confinement conditions. The Impact of the Justice Model on Juvenile Correctional Systems The states of Washington and California adopted the justice model through different approaches. However, both approaches had a profound effect on institutional populations . . Washington, in 1977, implemented a comprehensive justice model when the state legislature established mandatory sentencing standards requiring all adjudicated juvenile ... offenders between the ages of 8 and 17 to serve specified time periods in a correctional institution for specific offenses (Siegel and Senna, 1985). Within five years, the number of institutionalized youths in the State of Washington swelled, while confmement conditions deteriorated(Castellano 1986; Corsaletti 1991). Although the average length of stay in secure custody initia1ly declined, a higher percentage of . youth were committed to state correctional institutions. Since 1984, the average length of stay has increased every year (see Figure 5). Currently, the three main facilities are operating at 112% of capacity (The Children's Alliance 1991). The Washington juvenile correctional system is now the subject of a possible lawsuit over institutional conditions. After touring the state's juvenile training schools, attorneys from the National Center for Youth Law and the Youth Law Center noted that they were all in a state of decay. Programming was compromised for security concerns, while violence and abuse was pervasive. Staff maintain order through the use of police riot equipment, which includes a pepper-based eye spray that incapacitates disruptive youths. Washington's Department of Juvenile Rehabilitation consulting physician, Dr. James Owens, concluded that the product could cause permanent eye damage (David Lambert, National Center for Youth Law, personal interview, August 1991; Oaudia Wright, Youth Law Center, personal interview, May, 1991). One rationale underlying the Washington State reforms was the belief that recidivism would be lowered by increasing the certainty of punishment In her study on the effects of Washington's mandatory sentencing guidelines on juvenile recidivism, Schneider (1984) found that the new law had little impact on post release behavior and that in urban counties delinquent activity actually increased- This led Castellano (1986, p502) to conclude from his review of the Washington system that: " ... there is no evidence to suggest that the adoption of a 'just deserts' approach to juvenile offending has reducedjuveuile delinquency.", Center on Juvenile and Criminal Justice' 1622 Folsom Street· San Francisco, California 94103 PageS In California, unifonn confmement guidelines were adopted by the Youthful Offender Parole Board (YOPB) in 1978 following the implementation of the adult detenninate sentencing acl The YOPB, composed of gubernatorial appointees, establishes confinement lengths for all youths committed to the California Youth Authority (CYA) by the juvenile courts. Similar to the adult sentencing laws, the YOPB guidelines have been revised upwards on three occasions over the past 13 years. According to a recent report by the YOBP: The accompanying time intervals were established to be consistent with the time-setting intent described by the Legislature when mandatory sentences for adults committed to State prison were adopted. A still existing correlation was thus established between parole consideration dates and what was then the newly established determinate sentencing law. It was at that time that seven offense categories were identified and an appropriate time interval for each category was assigned (Youthful Offender Parole Board, Department of the Youth Authority, 1988). The YOPB utilizes seven categories to designate lengths of institutional stay based on the seriousness of the crime and the youth's prior record. Although California ostensibly maintains rehabilitation as a guiding principle, the State Legislature amended the juvenile court statutes in 1982 to include punishment as a disposition goal. . . .Minors under the jurisdiction of the juvenile court as a consequence of delinquent conduct shall, in conformity with the interests of public safety and protection, receive care, treatment and guidance which is consistent with their best interest, which holds them accountable for their behavior, and which is appropriate for their circumstances ... Such guidance may include punishment that is consistent with the rehabilitative objectives of this chapter .... (e) As used in this chapter, "punishment" means the imposition of sanctions which include the following: (1) Payment of a fine by the minor. (2) Rendering of compulsory service without compensation perfonned for the benefit of the community by the minor. (3) Limitations on the minor's liberty imposed as a condition of probation or parole. (4) Commitment of the minor to a local detention or treatment facility, such as a juvenile hall, camp, or ranch. Center on Juvenile and Criminal Justice' 1622 Folsom Street • San Francisco, California 94103 (5) Commitment of the minor to the Department of the Youth Authority (California Welfare and Institutions Code, Section 202) ... Page 6 This amendment legitimized the punitive nature of the California system and provided further impetus towards longer and more severe periods of incarceration. Within 12 years of the adoption of parole guidelines, the CY A population went from approllinately 47fJ7 to 7032 (California Youth Authority, Information Services, personal correspondence, September 24, 1991). The absence of a rehabilitative emphasis is evidenced by the large prison design and congregate dormitories. Like the reform schools of the past century, daily conditions in the CYA's 16 juvenile institutions are characterized by extreme . degrees of violence, intimidation, and idleness. Llttle meaningful intervention occurs as youths vie for dominance within a traditional prison subculture (Lerner 1986). The increase in incarceration was followed by a corresponding rise in recidivism rates. A study by the National Council on Crime and Delinquency, (NCCD) found an alarming 84 % rearrest rate for CY A parolees within three years of release (Baird 1987). In addition, a study by the CY A's own research division cited a rise in recidivism among parolees as periods of institutionalized confinement increased (Youthful Offender Parole Board, Department of the Youth Authority 1988) (See Figures 1 and 2). The expansion of the CY A population was unrelated to any increase in the crime rate or its severity. In 1988, the CYA was incarcerating a higher degree of less serious delinquent youth than they were in 1977 (see Figures 3 and 4). The justice model's vuInerability to political manipulation and meddling was evident from the start Since just punishment is a subjective judgement, calls for harsher sentences are easily accommodated within a punitive . oriented system (Cullen, Gilbert, 1981). Despite its past limitations, rehabilitation challenged . the propriety of conditions within institutions and offered a basis for the development of non- institutional alternatives. When this expectation was removed, the incentive among correctional . bureaucracies to improve conditions or maintain treatment was eliminated. Rehabilitation' and Organizational Commitment . While California and Washington were abandoning rehabilitation,Massachusetts and Utah were reaffirming it Recognizing the failure of the institutional model, Massachusetts in 1971, under the leadership of Commissioner Jerome G. Miller, closed its five juvenile correctional training schools (Ohlin, Coates, and Miller, 1978; Rutherford 1974; Bakal, Polsky, 1979). Center on Juvenile and Criminal Justice • 1622 folsom Street • San Francisco, California 94103 Page 7 Rather than abandon rehabilitation, Miller, on his own initiative, sought to redress the contradictions of the institutional system. He determined that the only way to eliminate institutional violence and abuses was to abolish the training school system. Between 1971 and 1973 all five of the Massachusetts training schools were closed. They were replaced by a network of small community based programs operating in neighborhoods throughout the state. These reforms were the most dramatic in the history of corrections in America. Never had an established correctional bureaucracy been so completely altered and recast. Nliller envisioned that the closing of the institutions would allow the juvenile justice system to finally pursue its original goal of humane individualized treatment (Ohlin, Coates, and Nliller 1978; Rutherford 1978; Polsky and Bakal, 1978). While the initial disruptions and uncertainties resulted in a political backlash and the eventual departure of Commissioner Miller, the closing of the institutions was irreversible. As Nliller's successors consolidated the reforms, a consensus developed reinforcing the propriety of the changes (Ohlin, Miller, & Coates, Rutherford, 1976; Polsky & Bakal, 1978). Following the Massachusetts example, Utah in 1980 closed its one 450-bed training school and shifted youths to community-based programs. As in Massachusetts, money that formerly was spent maintaining institutions went toward contracting with private agencies in local communities and neighborhoods. Services were designed to meet the demands of youths . with diverse needs and circumstances. For the few youths who required secure confinement, Utah maintains two 35-bed intensive treatment programs (Van Fleet, Rutherford, Schwartz, 1987). With a flexible range of programs, the state was able to invest heavily in providing high quality treatment services for its chronic and violent offenders in secure confinement. What distinguishes these programs from the past large congregate institutions is the absence of a prison subculture. Treatment is comprehensive and individualized. For those youths requiring non-secure custody, intensive outreach and tracking programs are provided in their home and neighborhoods. This treatment is offered at a fraction of the cost of secure residential treatment or confinement (Krisberg, Austin, Joe, Steele, 1988). A study by the National Council on Crime and Delinquency (NeCD) found a 66% decline in the frequency of subsequent arrests for youths released from Utah· s juvenile correctional programs during a twelve month follow-up. This "suppression effect" led NeeD researchers to conclude: .... therecidivism data for Youth Corrections offenders strongly indicate that the imposition of appropriate community-based controls on high! y active serious and chronic juvenile offenders is consistent with public protection goals. The Center on Juvenile and Criminal Justice' 1622 Folsom Street· San Francisco, California 94103 Page 8 well-structured ccmmunity-based programs of Utah' s Division of Youth Corrections may well constitute an important new range of dispositional options for handling serious and chronic juvenile offenders (Krisberg, Austin, Joe, Steele, 1988). Comparing Rehabilitation Models with Justice Models Of the 1,600 youths committed to the Massachusetts Department of Youth Services in 1990, only 15% are confined in locked secure-treatment programs. The majority of the committed population is spread throughout a variety of residential and nonresidential programs. Approximately 65% of these youths are maintained in their homes with supportive services (Loughran 1987). The programs utilized in Massachusetts and Utah include day treatment, temporary shelter care, intensive outreach and tracking, specialized foster care, wilderness adventure, group care, and secure residential (Lerner 1990). By contrast, 100% of first commitments to the California Youth Authority and 90% of the ccmmitted population to the Washington Division of Juvenile Rehabilitl.tion (DJR) are confined in secure correctional institutions. In addition, the average length of cont"inement in a California Youth Authority training school is now 24.7 months, while in Massachusetts the . average period of time in a secure program is 7.3 months. The vulnerabilitY of justice models to consistent increases in periods of incarceration is reflected in Figure S. Between 1982 and 1990, the average length of institutional confinement in Washington and California steadily .. increased, while it remained relatively stable in Utah. In addition, while yearly figures were . not available for Massachusetts, Department of Youth Service (DYS) officials assert that the average length of stay has remained constant (Executive Assistance to the Commissioner, Massachusetts Department of Youth Services, personal interview, September 1991). By correctional standards, conditions of confinement in secure facilities in Utah and Massachusetts are considered models of humane treatment, while youth correctional institutions in California and Washington are riddled by violence and decay (Lerner 1990, 1986; Corsaletti, 1991). In addition, a recent study concluded: . California now incarcerates a higher percentage of its youths for longer periods of time in larger and more secure facilities than any other major state in the . nation. Rates of incarceration at local and state levels are twice the national average (DeMuro, DeMuro & Lerner, 1988, p.IS). The differences in the four states is even more startling when census figures from the Office of Juvenile Justice and Delinquency Prevention (OJJDP) on youth in public custody Center on Juvenile and Criminal Justice·' 1622 Folsom Street • San Francisco, California 94103 Page 9 facilities is examined (see Figure 6). According to OJIDP researchers Thornberry, Tolnay, Flanagan, and Glynn (1991, p.16), public facilities, "whether short-term or long-term, were much more likely to be institutional." Additionally, there are extreme differences between states . in the number and type of committed youth placed in institutional confinement (See Figure 7). Reconsidering Rehabilitation The decline of rehabilitation was partly attributed to the perceived failure of researchers to demonstrate clearly that rehabilitation fostered lower rates of recidivism. According to Cullen and Gendreau (1989, p.38) "a reality has been constructed and legitimized by many criminologists that rehabilitation is a failed policy that the public will no longer tolerate." As a result of this pervasive perception, tougher sentencing and waivers to adult court became the dominant juvenile justice reform in the majority of states (Greenwood 1986). However, during the 1980s, new evidence emerged suggesting that the demise of rehabilitation was premature. A growing number of studies indicate that rehabilitative intervention is effective in de-escalating criminal behavior (Gendreau and Ross, 1987; Krisberg, Austin, Joe, Steele, 1987). Various well-designed interventions reduce the'severity and frequency of delinquency and alters the cycle that leads to adult crime. Studies have noted that approximately 40% of adult prison populations are graduates of institution-based juvenile justice systems (Rivers, Trotti, 1989). Thls finding is consistent with reviews of the adult prison population in Massachusetts prior to 1971. According to evaluations, since the reforms of20 years ago, the number of youths graduating to the adult criminal justice system in Massachusetts has fallen to 15% (Loughran 1987). A 1987 evaluation of the Massachusetts juvenile justice system by NCCD revealed a recidivism rate of 42 % as measured by the number of youths reconvicted of an offense after one year. When compared to four other states, Massachusetts had the lowest rates. In contrast, California, the most extreme example of a punitive institutional model, also recorded a .. reconviction rate of 53% (see Figure 8). Finally, only 23% of Massachusetts youth were reincarcerated after 36 months compared to California's rate of 62% (Krisberg, Austin & Steele, 1989) (See Figure 9). Well-developed and properly implemented rehabilitative programs are demonstrating tangible evidence of altering delinquent behavior and arrest patterns. For example, the Violent Juvenile Offender (VIO) Program was an experimental project designed to test the effectiveness of intensive programming for chronic and violent juvenile offenders. Services . were provided along a continuum starting with secure care and then progressing to community C~nter on Juvenile and Criminal Justice' 1622 Folsom Street· San Francisco, California 94103 Page 10 reintegration through intensive case management. The project was tested in four cities around the country. When recidivism results strongly favored the experimental group, researcher . Jeffrey Fagan (1990, p,258) concluded: The VJO Program tested a central proposition: carefully implemented and well- managed programs, rooted in sound theory and advanced practices, can effectively control violent juvenile crime and return offenders to their communities without risking community safety. The well-implemented programs resulted in significant reductions in the number and severity of arrests for experimental youths, as well as in significantly greater time until rearrest. The delays in return to crime for experimental youths during the critical first year following release suggest that the reintegration strategy also may be effective crime control. The positive effect of other well-designed and implemented intervention models continues to be recognized. An evaluation of the Vision Quest experiential education program, by the Rand Corporation, showed substantia.1ly lower rates of recidivism among Vision Quest graduates, compared to a matched sample of youthful offenders from a county training school in California. The lower recidivism occurred despite the fact that Vision Quest youths had considerably longer and more serious histories of delinquency. After a one year follow-up, Vision Quest youths had a recidivism rate of 55%, compared to the training school youths of 71 %. In addition, a smaller matched sample of CY A youths recorded a recidivism rate of 88%. Recidivism was measured by new arrests (Greenwood 1987). Another study conducted by the Oregon Social Learning Center tested the effectiveness of specialized foster care (SFC) for chronic delinquent youths who were diverted from state correctional institutions. Youths in the ex:perimental group were placed in specialized foster homes and provided with highly individualized treatment. Youths in the comparison group . were placed in traditional residential programs or facilities. One year after completing the program, experimental youths had dramatically lower reoffense rates, as measured by . subsequent reincarceration. According to Patterson (1987, pp. 10, 13): During the first year of follow-up post-treatment, 6 of 16 adolescents in the experimental group (38%) and 14 ofl6 in the control group (88%) were reinstitutionalized. .• . The results presented in this report provide preliminary support for the efficacy of applications of the SFC model. A study by Palmer and Wedge (1987) on county camps and ranches in California found that smaller individualized programs had rates of recidivism 18 % lower than those with more Center on Juvenile and Criminal Justice • 1622 Folsom Street • San Francisco, California 94103 " Page 11 traditional congregate institutional designs and practices. These differences were maintained even among youths with longer and more severe delinquent histories. The value of intensive case management was demonstrated in 1988 when the State of Maryland closed one of its two training schools by contracting with the National Center on Institutions and Alternatives (NClA). Under the plan, the State provided funding for the purchase of services on a case-by-case basis. Individualized service plans were implemented for 117 of the institution's most intractable youths. Case managers worked closely with youths to develop trust and understanding, while services were purchased from private-sector vendors according to each youths' circumstances and needs. A follow-up evaluation found that after one year only 35 youth were rearrested. Of those arrested, one was for a violent offense and only six were reincarcerated (Lerner 1990). Similar results were recorded by NClA's Hawaii Youth Advocacy Project NClA was contracted by the Hawaii Department of Corrections to initiate the process of deinstitutionalization through the closing of the Hawaii Youth Correctional Facility. Through intensive case management, 26 youths out of a total population of 75 were returned to the community within a six-month period. A follow-up evaluation found that only four were rearrested. This led criminologist Andrew Rutherford (1990, p. 19) to conclude: . As only 4 of the 26 releasees have been rearrested for further offences (for which charges were still pending and none of which involved violence), it is reasonable to conclude that the project was conducted without undue threat to public safety. Indeed, the results strongly suggest that the project has provided enhanced public protection through the new services provided during the three month follow-up period. The NCIA programs demonstrated the effectiveness of an intensive personalized approach to , providing services to the juvenile justice system's most troubled youth. The vital element in achieving success was the programs' vigorous advocacy and the ability of staff to form bonds with youths (Macallair, 1990). The positive results of the NClA programs was supported by Lipsey's (1990) recent meta analysis of juvenile correctional treatment programs. His analysis of 443 studies showed modest but positive results when they were reviewed in their totality. However, when various types of approaches were examined, dramatic results were observed. For example, Lipsey found that programs employing case work approaches could reduce recidivism by 10 to 20 percentage points. In contrast, programs administered by juvenile justice bureacracies yielded the least favorable results. Programs that used deterrence strategies such as shock incarceration . and "scared straight" approachs tended to escalate delinquent behavior (37-39). Center on Juvenile and Criminal Justice' 1622 Folsom Street· San Francisco, California 94103 Page 12 In their comprehensive review of the research on rehabilitation, Gendreau and Ross (1987) concluded that contrary to popular assumptions, the evidence overwhelming indicates that rehabilitation programs work. While not eliminating recidivism, rehabilitation is more effective than correctional institutions in reducing the rate and seriousness of criminal behavior. Conclusion An examination of juvenile justice in much of the United States reveals a system dominated by archaic 19th century correctional models and theories. Despite the doctrine of rehabilitation, the institution-based system is an unequivocal failure. As former Office of Juvenile Justice and Delinquency Prevention director, Ira Schwartz (1989, p. 169) notes: All large training schools should be closed. These institutions are expensive to operate and difficult to manage, and they simply don't work. They have no place in an enlightened and cost effective youth correctional system. Due to their past inabilities to alter institutional conditions, reformers have been rendered frustrated and disheartened. This situation led many to resign themselves to the institutional system and embrace the justice model in hopes of at least limiting periods of confinement. However, by abandoning rehabilitation, progressive advocates effectively disarmed themselves in the battle over juvenile justice policy. Legislative and bureaucratic debates came to center on degrees of punishment rather than its legitimacy. Under these conditions, conservatives were able to pursue their agenda of harsher punishments with little opposition. The acceptance of the justice model by the progressive community proved disastrous. Instead of reining in the power of the institutional system, it served to augment it. To regain the political momentum, reformers must reembrace rehabilitation. Rehabilitation enjoys broad public support as demonstrated in a recent California poIL In contrast to its current public policies, 82 % of California residents voiced their belief that the purpose' of the juvenile justice system should be the pursuit of rehabilitation (Wallace 1988). A commitment to rehabilitation will reignite efforts to dismantle the institution-based system. Those states and jurisdictions that have implemented effective rehabilitation programs . provide, models on which to build a new reinvigorated progressive agenda. However, a new commitment to rehabilitation will require a resurgence of activism among the progressive . community. A return to rehabilitation is presently the only viable strategy for achieving reductions in custodial confinement and promoting the humane and effective treatment of troubled youths. Center on Juvenile and Criminal Justice' 1622 Folsom Streer • San Francisco, California 94103 '. " 0.7 0.6 0.5 0.4 OJ 0.2 0.1 O. FlGlJRE 1 PERCE.'iTAGE OF PEOPLE LSSCCCESSFCLLY TER.\lI.'iATED fRml PAROLE 1979 1982 ., ' 1979·48.5% 1982·55.7% 1985·61.8% 1985 Source: California Youth Authoritv FlGlJRE 2 A \ "[RAGE LE.\GTH OF STA Y AT 20 1 RELEASE FOR FIRST 181 COmllThlEm 16 ~ (P.i MO~lHS) 14 12 10 8 6 4 2 o 1979 1982 1979· 12,6 1982· 15,0 1985 ·19.1 19&5 Source: California Youth Authority FlGFRE3 Type of Crime - Offenses committed by those entering CY A institutions for the first time (1977) 0.6 0.4 0.2 Ol---'"->- Drugs Property Violent Others FlGFRE .j Sourc.e: California Type of Crime· Offenses romrnittl'd by Youth Authority; those entering CYA institutions for the California Legislative first time (1988) Analyst 0.45 0.4 0.35 OJ 0.25 0.2 0.15 0.1 I 0.05 o Drugs Property Violent Drugs - 2.5% Property - 45.3' Violent - 45.1 ~ Others - 7.1 % • Drugs Il!I Property E! Violent Il Others Others Drugs· 14% Property - 43.6 % Violent - 36.l % Others - 6.3 % I Drugs ill Property C Violent l1W Others " fIGURE 5 iherage Length of Stay in Sffure Custody 30 1- (in months) 25 /::l::-::l::_X 20 I .___X-::t:.--- X i,----::l:: ::l:: ] 5 1 X- California .~- Utah 10 f .~ 6--~--~- ~==~~ • • ~.--.--+--. ~ 5~ o I '. • Washington 19831984198519861987198819891990 Figure 6 Youth in Public Custody Facilities Per 100,000 National Average "California Massachusetts Utah "Washington 1987 1989 208 221 496 535 42 48 88 85 229 236 Source: OffiCe of Juvenile Ju>tice and D<:linqueDcy mvention • California bas the highest rate among all states. wrule Washington rank,; eighth. M.-I.SSACHUS errs UTAH WASHr-lGTON Source,; FlGURE 7 SECURE CU>TODY COMP."-RlSONS ·1990 A .... en.gc Daily PopulAtion in $.cCLI!"e Confinement 112 70 587 Perce nttge of FL."'1t Time Commilmcnts in Secure Cl.!slc>dy 100% IS% 16% 909<. California. YClUth Aulhority, lr.rOiIT.~iOIl Services A.'crate t.c.gth of Average Num~of SL!)' in So:urc Cor.ft!"lerncnt Prior Sustrined Pr::utioos (in monL'u) for Yo~ui l.n Secure Cus!od;Z 24.7 2.9 8.0 N/A 7.5 9.0 6.3 N/A MUs.1chusel:ts De;>a.:'f.mcnt of Youth SCO\'i~s, E"e>:'utivc ,A.ssis:.!J\t to the Commissioner UL1.h OJ''ision of Youth COcrec:.iODS, Res~'"Ch AnAlyst St.a.lc: of Uu.h. AdministrAtive Office ofthc CoutU V.'a~hln&1on Division of Rehabilitative Services, lnfonnaLion Sys~ems Coordinator FlGURE8 0.6 i PERCEXTAGE OF PAROLEES 0.5 RECO:-'''\"lCTED 0,4 OJ 0.2 0.1 o Massachusetts California Massachusetts - 42 % California - 55% • Massachusetts l!!D California Source: Natiooal Council on rnm~ anti ~llnl1l1pn{'v 0.7 CJH . 61cr I omla· ./e Massachusetts· 22 % 0.6 0.5 0.4 OJ 0.2 0.1 0 Massachusetts F1GURE9 PERCE\TAGE OF PAROLEES REl\CARCERUED mTHl\ 36 ~lO\THS California OF RELEASE • Massachusetts !!!lI Cali f 0 rnia Source: National Council 0 Crime and Delinquency REFEREC'iCES Austin, I., B. Krisberg (1981) Wider Stronger, and Different Nets: The Dialectics of Criminal Iustice Reform. Crime and Delinquency: pp. 165-193. Bakal, Y., H.W. Polsky (1979) Reforming Corrections for Iuvenile Offenders. Lexington, MA: Lexington Books. California Youth Authority, Youthful Offender Parole Board. 1988. Youth Authority Institutionall.ength of Stay and Recidivism, California Iuvenile Arrest Rates, and Guidelines for Parole Consideration Dates. Sacramento, CA. State of California. Castellano, T. C. (1986) The Iustice Model in the Iuvenile Iustice System: Washington State's Experience. Law and Policy. Vol. 8 No.4. 479-506. Chamberlain, P. (1988) Treatment of Chronic Delinquents in Specialized Foster Care: A Matched Comparison Study. Eugene, OR: Oregon Social Learning Center. The Children's Alliance (1991) The State of the Child: A Selected Statistical Overview. Seattle, W A: The Children's Alliance. Corsaletti, L T. (1991, Iuly 16) Overcrowding at Echo Glen: New Urgency to Old Lawsuit. Seattle Times, pp. 1-2. Corsaletti, L T. (1991, August 2) Youth Center's Staff Swamped: State Panel Told of Attacks, Stress. Seattle Times, P.IO. Coates, R. B., A.D. Miller, LE. Ohlin (1978) Diversity in a Youth Correctional System. Cambridge, MA: Ballinger. Cullen, F. T., P. Gendreau (1989) 'The Effectiveness of Correctional Rehabilitation: Reconsidering the "Nothing Works' Debate.' pp. 23-44. In Lynne Goodstein and Doris Layton Mackenzie (eds), The American Prison: Issues in Research and Policy. New York, NY: Plenum Press. Cullen, F. T., K.E.Gilbert (1982) Reaffirming Rehabilitation. Cincinnati, Ohio: Anderson Publishing Co. DeMuro, P., A. DeMuro, S. Lerner (1988) Reforming the CYA: How to End CrOWding and Diversify Treatment and Protect the Public Without Spending More Money. Bolinas, CA.: Commonweal Research institute. Empey, L (1982) American Delinquency: Its Meaning and Construction. Homewood, Illinois, The Dorsey Press. Fagan, 1. A. (1990) Treatment and Reintegration of Violent Iuvenile Offenders: Experimental Results. Iustice Quarterly Vol. 7: 233-263. Fogel, D. (1975) "We are the Living Proof...? The Iustice Model for Corrections. Cincinnati, OR .. ""'derson. Gendreau, P., R.R. Ross (1987) Revivification of Rehabilitation: Evidence from the 1980's. Iustice Quarterly Vol. 4 No.3. 249-407 Greenwood, P. (1987) An Evaluation of the Vision Quest Program. Santa Monica, CA.: Rand Greenwood, P. (1986) Iuvenile Offenders. Washington, DC: United States Department ofJustice, National " Institute of Corrections. Greenwood, P. W .. F.E. Zimring (1985) One More Chance: The Pursuit of Promising Strategies for Chronic Juvenile Offenders. Santa Monica, CA: Rand Klein, M., S.Kobrin (1980) National Evaluation of the Deinstitutionalization of Status Offender Programs: Executive Summary. Los Angeles, CA: Social Science Research Institute. Krisberg, B., J.Austin, P. A. Steele (1989). Unlocking Juvenile Corrections: Evaluating the Massachusetts Department of Youth Services. National Council on Crime and Delinquency. San Francisco, CA. Krisberg, B., J. Austin, K. Joe, P. Steele (1988) The Impact of Juvenile Court Sanctions. San Francisco, CA: National Council on Crime and Delinquency. Krisberg, B., I.M. Schwartz, P. Utsky, J. Austin, (January, 1986) The Watershed of Juvenile Justice Reform. Crime and Delinquency, Vo1.32: 5-37 Krisberg, B., J. Austin (1978). The Children of Ishmael. Palo Alto, CA: Mayfield Publishing Company. Lerman, P. (1975) Community Treatment and Social Control: A Critical Analysis of Juvenile Correctional Policy. Chicago, II. University of Chicago Press. Lerner, S. (1990) The Good News About Juvenile Justic~: The Movement Away from Large Institutions and Toward Community-Based Services. Bolinas, CA: Commonweal Research Press. Lerner, S. (1986) Bodily Harm: The Pattern of Fear and Violence at the California Youth Authority. Bolinas, CA: Commonweal Research Institute. Uef, J. G. (1988) A History of the Internal Organization of the State Reform School for Boys at Westborough, Massachusetta (1846-1974). Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA. Upsey, M. W. (1990). Juvenile Delinquency Treatment: A Meta-analytic Inquiry into the Variability of Effect. Claremont, CA: Claremont Graduate School. Upton, D., R. Martinson, J. Wilks, (1975) The Effectiveness of Correctional Treatment: A Survey of Treatment Evaluation Studies. New York, NY: Praeger. Loughran, E. (1987) "Juvenile Corrections: The Massachusetts Experience." Pp 7-18 in In Reinvesting Youth Corrections Resources: A Tale of Three States, edited by Lee Edison. Ann Arbor: Center for the Study of Youth Policy, University of Michigan. Macallair, D. (1990) ACLU's Demands Trigger Change in Hawaii's Juvenile Justice System. National Prison Project Journal Spring: 5-6. Palmer, T., R. Wedge (1989) California's Juvenile Probation Camps: Findings and Implications. Crime an.d Delinquency, Vol. 35: 234-235. Palmer, T., M. Bohnstedt, R. Lewis (1978) The Evaluation of Juvenile Diversion Projects: Final Report. Sacramento, CA: The California Youth Authority. President's Commission on Law Enforcement and Administration of Justice. (1967a) The Challenge of Crime in a Free Society. Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office. ---(1967b) Task Force Report: Juvenile Delinquency and Youth Crime. Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office. Rivers, J., T. Trotti (1989) South Carolina Delinquent Males: A Follow-up Into Adult Corrections. Columbia, SC. South Carolina Department of Youth Services. , work_366nm2h3zvg5toqetojpv54hyq ---- PDF hosted at the Radboud Repository of the Radboud University Nijmegen The following full text is a publisher's version. For additional information about this publication click this link. http://hdl.handle.net/2066/111686 Please be advised that this information was generated on 2021-04-06 and may be subject to change. http://hdl.handle.net/2066/111686 Justice in transport as justice in accessibility: applying Walzer’s ‘Spheres of Justice’ to the transport sector Karel Martens � The Author(s) 2012. This article is published with open access at Springerlink.com Abstract This paper seeks to provide a theoretical basis for a distributive approach to transport. Using the theory developed by Michael Walzer in his ‘Spheres of Justice’ (1983), I argue that the transport good, defined as accessibility, should be distributed in a so-called separate sphere, i.e. independent from the way in which other key goods, like money or power, are allocated. I subsequently explore what kind of justice principle could guide the distribution of the transport good, once a separate sphere would be established. This preliminary exploration results in the elimination of a number of widely supported distributive principles, and in the tentative identification of a criterion matching the par- ticularities of the transport good. The explorations in the paper are not intended as final answers, but rather seek to open the debate about the need for an explicit distributive transport policy and the distributive principle that should guide such a policy. Keywords Transport � Justice � Equity � Spheres of Justice � Distribution Introduction Transport has become a key field of government intervention in modern societies. Governments do not only set the regulatory framework, but also determine the size and scope of investments in transport facilities. Given the importance of transport in current highly mobile societies, the way in which governments distribute transport over their citizens becomes of the utmost importance. And yet, while an extensive body of literature exists on transport and (environmental) justice (see Schweitzer and Valenzuela 2004), little has been said about the desirability or (im)possibility of a distributive approach to transport. The goal of this paper is to explore transport as a field of government intervention through a distributive lens. While a wide variety of approaches to social justice can be distinguished (see Fabre 2007 for an overview), the explorations presented here start from K. Martens (&) Institute for Management Research, Radboud University Nijmegen, Nijmegen, The Netherlands e-mail: k.martens@fm.ru.nl 123 Transportation DOI 10.1007/s11116-012-9388-7 Walzer’s ‘Spheres of Justice’ (Walzer 1983). 1 There are two main motivations for this choice. First, to the best of our knowledge, Walzer’s approach has not yet been applied to transport. Second, and more importantly, many of the major theories of justice, among which Rawl0s theory of ‘justice as fairness’, relate to the basic structure of a society rather than to particular institutions within a society (Fabre 2007, pp. 19–20). While such theories can be applied to the field of transport (see Beatley 1988 for an application of Rawls’ difference principle to transport), such applications will not provide an answer to the question why a distributive approach is called for in the case of transport. In contrast, as will be argued below, Walzer’s theory can provide such a theoretical foundation for a distributive approach to transport. The paper starts with a brief account of Walzer’s theory of justice (‘‘Walzer’s Spheres of Justice’’ section). This results in the identification of three questions: (1) What is the social meaning of the transport good (‘‘The social meaning of the transport good’’ section); (2) Does the social meaning of the transport good justify the creation of a so-called separate sphere around the good? (‘‘Transportation as a field of policy intervention’’ and ‘‘Transport as a separate sphere’’ sections); and (3) Which distributive principle should guide the allocation of the transport good? (‘‘Towards a distributive principle for trans- port’’ section). Taken together, the answers to these questions provide a tentative theo- retical basis for a distributive approach to transport. The character of the paper is explorative. It cannot address all the issues related to a distributive approach to transport, such as the importance of the land use–transport interaction or the personal responsibility of people in choosing e.g. their place of residence or means of transport, all of which directly affect justice in transport. As a result, the paper does not aim to provide final answers, but rather aims to trigger a debate about the need for a distributive approach to transport. The paper draws, amongst others, on the rather dispersed body of literature that con- nects transport and distributive justice. This literature includes papers that explicitly apply philosophies of social justice to transport (e.g., Lucy 1988; Khisty 1996), empirical studies into the distribution of a wide variety of transport-related benefits and burdens (see ‘‘The social meaning of the transport good’’ section for a number of references), studies into urban service delivery (e.g., Miranda and Tunyavong 1994; Talen and Anselin 1998; Neutens et al. 2010a), as well as the vast literature on spatial mismatch (see ‘‘Transport as a separate sphere’’ section), the growing number of publications on transport and social exclusion (see ‘‘Transport as a separate sphere’’ section), and more recent explorations into the ethics of mobility (e.g., Bergman and Sager 2008) and the ethics and distributive impacts of transportation planning (e.g., Martens 2006; Martens and Hurvitz 2011; Martens (2011); Van Wee 2011). It is well beyond the scope of the paper to provide a review of this diverse body of literature. For insightful reviews into a large part of the literature, see Schweitzer and Valenzuela (2004) and Schweitzer and Stephenson (2007). Walzer’s Spheres of Justice The theoretical starting point for the proposed justice approach to transport is Walzer’s ‘Spheres of Justice’ (Walzer 1983, 1995). In line with most other contemporary scholars 1 Throughout the paper the term justice is employed, rather than the terms equity or fairness. While each of these terms may refer to different concepts in certain contexts, in common usage the terms strongly overlap and are used interchangeably. See also Hay (1995). Transportation 123 (but see Young 1990), Walzer takes a distributive approach to social justice by asking the question how benefits and burdens are and should be distributed over members of society. However, unlike other scholars of social justice like e.g. Rawls (1971), he does not focus on the distribution of an abstract set of basic goods. Rather, he views society as a dis- tributive community in which people produce a wide variety of goods that are subsequently shared, divided and exchanged in specific ways. These goods, according to Walzer, can neither be reduced to a set of abstract goods, nor be idiosyncratically valued. Goods are, by definition, social goods; their meaning is socially constructed. ‘‘Goods (…) have shared meanings because conception and creation are social processes’’ (Walzer 1983, p. 7). Subsequently, goods can have different meanings in different societies; the same ‘thing’ may be valued in one place, while it is hardly valued or even disvalued in another. Likewise, goods with a comparable ‘market value’ may differ fundamentally from a dis- tributive perspective, because they differ in terms of the social meaning members of particular society attach to them. Precisely because of these differences in the social meaning of goods, Walzer argues, there can be no single criterion in virtue of which all goods are to be made available to members of society. Commonly defended criteria like free exchange, need or desert cannot determine the distribution of all goods available in society. Furthermore, distributive criteria and arrangements are intrinsic not to the good-in- itself but to the social good: ‘‘If we understand what it is, what it means to those for whom it is a good, we understand how, by whom, and for what reasons it ought to be distributed’’ (ibid., p. 9). The social meaning of a good is therefore of crucial importance in Walzer’s approach. It is the basis for determining what constitutes a fair distribution: ‘‘All distri- butions are just or unjust relative to the social meanings of the goods at stake’’ (ibid., p. 9). Based on this ‘theory of goods’—only briefly summarized here—Walzer then develops the concept of ‘distributive spheres’. Distributive spheres are the prerogative of goods that have a distinct social meaning in a particular society, which sets them apart from regular goods. While regular goods, like necklaces or mobile phones, may also have a social meaning, they can be distributed through the market and their distribution can be deter- mined through the principle of free exchange. Goods to which a particular society ascribes a distinct social meaning, in contrast, are to be taken out of the sphere of free exchange. Typical examples in modern Western societies are health and education. These and comparable goods, Walzer argues, ‘deserve’ their own distributive sphere. For Walzer, a distributive sphere is characterized by two basic features. First, it requires that the distribution of a particular good be guided by another distributive principle than free exchange. As discussed, these principles can differ—ranging from equality to need— but are to match the social meaning of the good in a particular society (Trappenburg 2000). Second, a distributive sphere should guarantee that the distribution of the particular good is autonomous from the way in which other goods are distributed. According to Walzer, injustice occurs if spheres are not autonomous. In that case, the distribution of one good or one set of goods can become dominant and determine the distributions in all, or many, spheres of distribution. Typically, according to Walzer, money and power are the goods to claim dominance, and much of the policy debates, like those in the fields of basic education or health services, are about limiting their domination. Ultimately, autonomy guarantees what Walzer terms ‘complex equality’: a situation in which inequalities within spheres may exist, but in which the autonomy of distributive spheres will guarantee that inequalities will not necessarily sum up across different goods or spheres. Walzer’s approach is certainly not without problems (see e.g., Dworkin 1983b; Teuber 1984; Fabre 2007). Its strength lies in the theoretical foundation it provides for the political reality in modern societies. In modern societies, government intervention is not concerned Transportation 123 with the distribution of abstract primary goods, such as those distinguished by Rawls (1971), but with the distribution of a wide variety of real, tangible, goods. Prominent among these are income, education, health care, and housing. Principles of justice play a central role in the distribution of each of these goods, although these principles may differ between societies. The importance of Walzer’s theory of justice, and its core concept of spheres, lies in the fact that it can provide a theoretical foundation for a distributive approach to transport. From Walzer’s perspective, a distributive approach to a particular good is called for if that good has a distinct social meaning: ‘When meanings are distinct, distributions must be autonomous’ (Walzer 1983, p. 10—author’s emphasis). If this condition holds for the transport good, i.e. if the transport good has a socially distinct meaning, than a distributive approach to transport can be justified. Walzer’s theory of justice thus raises three key questions for the field of transport. The first concerns the social meaning of the transport good (‘‘The social meaning of the transport good’’ section). Only if a clear social meaning can be ascribed to the transport good, is it fruitful to enter a discussion about the relevance of a separate transport sphere. The second, and perhaps principal, question is whether the social meaning ascribed to the transport good is distinct enough to draw boundaries around the good and set it apart from other goods and create a separate ‘transport sphere’ (‘‘Transportation as a field of policy intervention’’ and ‘‘Transport as a separate sphere’’ sections). Then, if the answer to this second query is yes, the third question is how the transport good should be distributed, i.e. which distributive principle is appropriate to guide the allocation of the transport good (‘‘Towards a distributive principle for transport’’ section). Below, I turn to each of these three questions. The social meaning of the transport good The first question raised by Walzer’s approach concerns the social meaning of what has thus far been referred to as ‘the transport good’. Obviously, and in line with the critique of Dworkin (1983a), the demarcation of the social meaning of the transport good is not a simple one. Opinions may differ widely between and within societies, depending on people’s backgrounds, perspectives and personal lives. Hence, the discussion below is not a final answer, but a first attempt to demarcate a social meaning that might be widely shared in modern, industrialized, societies. First, when people relate to transport, it is about the possibilities it offers to travel to places, to access people and opportunities, or to experience the freedom to escape one’s locality (see e.g. the contributions in Bergman and Sager 2008). The social meaning of the transport good therefore seems to lie in the benefits related to transport, rather than in the burdens. Even in academic discourse, the burdens related to transport, such as greenhouse gas emissions, are defined as negative externalities, emphasizing that they are not a core part of the transport good. This suggests that the distribution of the transport good should first and foremost be guided by the benefits that are related to it, rather than based on the burdens it may generate. This is a fundamental point, as much of the debate on transport and equity has focused precisely on the distribution of transport-related burdens (e.g., Feitelson 2002; Forkenbrock and Schweitzer 1999; Schweitzer and Valenzuela 2004). Walzer’s approach does not suggest that the distribution of these burdens is not a matter of justice. In line with his theory, it can actually be argued that in current Western societies, a healthy environment is Transportation 123 a good with a distinct social meaning that deserves to be set apart from other goods. Walzer’s approach thus suggests that the distribution of the transport-related environmental burdens should be related to environmental burdens from other sources and that their distribution should be jointly considered. The principle guiding the distribution of the total set of environmental burdens should subsequently be derived from the social meaning ascribed to a healthy environment. Note that the desired distributions in the ‘environment sphere’ may well have implications for the possible distributions in the ‘transport sphere’. It is beyond the scope of the paper to further explore this issue. For now, it suffices to conclude that Walzer’s emphasis on the social meaning of a good as the basis for its distribution, suggests that the benefits of transport should be the starting point for the debate about the distribution of the transport good. Second, it may be clear that the transport good as such does not exist. The good— however conceptualized—is a combination of objects like cars and bicycles; artifacts like roads and railways; services like public transport lines, car repair services and guarded parking facilities; and less tangible goods like driving licenses, traffic regulations or route guidance systems. In this sense, the transport good is comparable to a good like basic education, explicitly discussed by Walzer in his book. Like transport, basic education is not a concrete good that is transferred from one person to another. Basic education as a social good is the outcome of the combination of a multitude of tangible and less tangible goods: class rooms, teachers, school books, teaching materials, learning methods, etcetera. These goods combine to the good which Walzer refers to as ‘mediated education’: the systematic transfer of knowledge and skills to pupils and students. It is this good, rather than the different parts constituting it, which, according to Walzer, should be set apart in a separate sphere and distributed in a way compatible with the social meaning of the good in a particular society (Walzer 1983, pp. 197–226). Following this line of reasoning, the distributive question in transport does not relate to the individual objects, artifacts, etc. that constitute the ‘transport good’, as the social meaning of each of these parts stems from the social meaning of the overarching ‘transport good’. Following Walzer, it is the social meaning of the overarching good that should provide the compass for the distribution of the good over members over society. The allocation of the composite parts should be derived from this; not the other way around. This is, again, a fundamental point, as much of the literature and policy debates on distributive justice in transport have focused on precisely the composite parts, such as road and gasoline taxes (Altshuler 1979); transit investments and subsidies (Cervero 1981; Hodge 1988; Garrett and Taylor 1999); infrastructure investments (Lucy 1988; Bröcker et al. 2010); road user charges (Smeed 1964; Richardson 1974; Ecola and Light 2009); and transit service (Murray and Davis 2001; Rucker 1984; Wu and Hine 2003). For Western societies, and increasingly so for non-Western societies, and in line with much of the transport literature, two distinct meanings of the overarching transport good can be distinguished: potential mobility and accessibility (e.g., Garb and Levine 2002; Vigar 1999). Potential mobility, often simply referred to as mobility, refers to the ease with which a person can move through space (e.g., Sager 2005). Since the term mobility is frequently used to describe the (growth in the) actual movement of people, I explicitly distinguish between mobility and potential mobility, or movement and potentiality of movement (Kaufmann 2002, pp. 13–14). An increase in mobility implies that a person travels over longer distances, more frequently, or both. In contrast, an increase in potential mobility only implies an increase in a person’s capacity to overcome distance in space—it does not imply the actual realization of this capacity (Sager 2005, pp. 3–4). Transportation 123 Accessibility has a meaning quite distinct from potential mobility. It refers to the ease with which destinations can be reached from a given location in space (see e.g., Farrington and Farrington 2005; Dong et al. 2006; Niemeier 1997). Two different forms of accessi- bility have been distinguished in the literature: person accessibility and place accessibility. While the terms are often used interchangeably, it is important to clarify the difference between them (see Pirie 1979; Kwan 1999; Miller 2007 for more elaborate discussions). Person accessibility is an attribute of a person: a person has accessibility (or not) to a certain set of locations. Place accessibility, in turn, is an attribute of an (activity) location: a location is accessible (or inaccessible) for a certain set of people or from a certain set of other locations. Person and location accessibility are thus each other’s mirror image (Fig. 1). The distributive perspective taken in this paper directs the attention to people rather than locations, as people and not locations are the recipients of socially valued goods. Hence, from a distributive perspective person and not place accessibility should be the focus of analysis. Both the concepts of potential mobility and of person accessibility—in the remainder of the paper simply referred to as accessibility—are directly related to a wider system of values dominating Western societies. The conceptualization of the transport good as potential mobility can be linked to notions such as freedom of movement and freedom of choice. (Potential) mobility is often even equated with freedom of movement (e.g., Cresswell 2006), although the latter refers to a right rather than to a capacity varying in strength. Freedom of choice and potential mobility are strongly intertwined—with a high level of potential mobility implying a high level of choice in terms of employment opportunities, health care services, leisure facilities, and so forth. Mobility is also closely linked to widely cherished values such as open-mindedness, discovery, experience and adventure (Kaufmann 2002, p. 37), and to notions like escape and autonomy (Zeitler 1999, pp. 21–22; Lomasky 1997). Perhaps most importantly, high (potential) mobility is linked to the ambition to break the tether of physical friction—a desire enshrined in Western society and exemplified in the expansion of the Roman empire, the discoveries, and the search for speed since the industrial revolution (Couclelis 1996; Harvey 1990; Sager 2005). The concept of accessibility also has deep roots in Western value systems. Accessibility indicates ability, i.e. the ability to accomplish a broad range of actions, by linking to places and people that are set apart in space and time (Talen 2001). As such, accessibility is also ** ** ** ** ** ** ** ** ** ** ** ** ** ** ** ** ** ** ** (b)(a) ** ** ** ** ** ** ** ** ** ** ** ** ** ** ** ** ** ** ** Fig. 1 Person accessibility (a) versus place accessibility (b). The borders of each diagram indicate the area that can be travelled within e.g. a certain time budget or time-money budget. Source Dijst (1995, p. 28). ** = person, j = activity location Transportation 123 linked to freedom of choice, with higher levels of accessibility indicating higher levels of choice and hence a higher potential for personal fulfillment and satisfaction. Yet, at the same time, accessibility also stresses that choice and freedom of movement are limited: a person has accessibility to certain places but not to others, a person has the ability to accomplish certain actions but not others. Accessibility, precisely because it links transport to land use, stresses the fact that space creates a friction, a barrier between origin and desired destination. Moreover, the notion of accessibility pre-supposes knowledge about destinations (see Kwan and Hong 1998 for an empirical study), thus eliminating conno- tations of adventure, discovery or even new experience, so closely intertwined with potential mobility. Accessibility as a concept is thus at odds with key values of Western society like autonomy and freedom, by underscoring the place-boundedness of people, bounded as they are to an ‘origin’ and a given set of destinations, linked together by a known set of links. In this sense, accessibility contrasts starkly with potential mobility, which stresses freedom rather than limitations, endlessness rather than place-boundedness, and autonomy rather dependence. It thus seems that potential mobility rather than accessibility has the firmest roots in Western culture. This may also explain—at least to some extent—why (potential) mobility rather than accessibility has been the locus of much of transportation planning in the twentieth century (see e.g., Vigar 1999; Cervero et al. 2001). Yet, it can be argued that ultimately accessibility best reflects the social meaning of the transport good in Western societies. The emphasis in popular discourse on potential mobility, as reflected in values like freedom of movement, is a result of an individualistic approach to mobility. For a given person in a given space–time setting, a higher level of potential mobility always implies more choice, more experience, more adventure, and, ultimately, more freedom. However, this conceptualization is fundamentally flawed in a comparative perspective. Because space is neither a uniform nor a static entity, households with comparable levels of potential mobility may well differ fundamentally in the level of choice, the possibility of adventure, and the level of freedom they experience (Fig. 2). Hence, in a comparative perspective, potential mobility cannot be equated directly with key values like choice, experience or freedom. This, in turn, suggests that it would be incorrect to equate the transport good with potential mobility. Because, if the distribution of potential mobility does not necessarily correlate with the distribution of more fundamental, and highly ** (a) (b) ** Fig. 2 Potential mobility and choice level. The person in diagram (a) has the same level of potential mobility as the person in diagram (b), as indicated by the identical size of the diagram. However, person (a) has a substantial higher level of choice of activity locations than person (b). Figure based on Dijst (1995, p. 29). ** = person, j = activity location Transportation 123 valued, goods, it can hardly be defended as a proper conceptualization of the social meaning of transport in society. Ultimately, transport is first and foremost a derived ‘need’ (e.g., Rimmer 1985); the social meaning of the good should therefore also be derived from the underlying needs. Since accessibility, in contrast to potential mobility, does link transport to these underling needs, I argue that accessibility rather than potential mobility best captures the social meaning of transport in current Western societies. This concep- tualization is in line with the increasing number of studies into the distribution of acces- sibility over different population groups (e.g. Kawabata and Shen 2007; Hess 2005; Benenson et al. 2010) building on much earlier work in this direction (e.g. Wachs and Kumagai 1973; Black and Conroy 1977), and the rising attention for accessibility in transportation planning, as highlighted by a.o. Garb and Levine (2002), Cervero et al. (2001), and Bertolini et al. (2005). Note that person accessibility is shaped by a wide range of factors, such as mode availability, money and time budgets, or the temporal organization of society, all of which create disparities in accessibility levels between different persons (e.g., Kwan 2000; Neutens et al. 2010b). Furthermore, the focus on person accessibility still leaves unad- dressed the question how person accessibility should be measured. As illustrated by a number of authors, the type of accessibility measure has significant ramifications for the representation of differences in person accessibility (e.g., Kwan 1998; Neutens et al. 2010a) and, hence, for preferred policy responses (e.g., Lucy 1981). This important issue requires a separate discussion that will be left to another occasion; for a first exploration rooted in the social justice literature, see Martens and Golub (in press). Finally, it should be noted that the identification of accessibility as the good that best captures the social meaning of transport has implications for the conceptualization of a separate sphere. It suggests that this sphere does not coincide with the traditional demarcation of transport as a field of government intervention, as the distribution of accessibility is also strongly shaped by other fields of policy intervention, like spatial planning or various types of service delivery policies. Note that the good of accessibility does not differ in this respect from a good like ‘health’, as the distribution of the latter, too, is not only determined by health care in a narrow sense, but also by government programs to provide e.g. proper sanitation (Daniels 2008). Below, I will abstract from this compli- cation for now and assume, in order to further develop the argument, that land use patterns are given and accessibility levels are primarily shaped through transport-related inter- ventions (typically, investments in transport infrastructure and services). In a future paper, I aim to relax this strongly simplifying assumption and explore its consequences for the framework outlined here. Transportation as a field of policy intervention Now that the social meaning of the transport good is more clearly demarcated, it is possible to turn to the second question raised by Walzer’s approach: Does the transport good, defined as accessibility, deserve to be set apart from other goods and distributed in a separate sphere? A likely first response to this question may be that transport as a clearly demarcated field of policy intervention has, by and large, already created a separate sphere around the good of accessibility. More specifically, it could be argued that the policy field of transport, through large-scale investments in transport infrastructure and services, already strongly shapes the distribution of accessibility levels over members of society. While this can hardly be denied, I would argue that the transport field has hardly created Transportation 123 a truly distributive, Walzer-like, sphere around the socially valued good of accessibility, even if we would abstract from the strong interrelationship between transport and land use. Three interrelated arguments can support this claim. First, in traditional transport planning, explicit distributive considerations seem to play a secondary role at best. What guides most transport planning efforts in the industrialized world is a systems perspective. Policy success is first and foremost measured in terms of the performance of (parts of) the transport system, and hardly in terms of how various groups in society benefit from policy measures (Khisty and Zeitler 2001). A clear symbol of this line of thinking is the use of the level-of-service criterion, which guides much of the investments in the road system (e.g. de Dios Ortuzar and Willumsen 2001). This criterion is merely an indicator of the performance of separate links of the road network, i.e. the extent to which ‘free flow’ traffic conditions occur on each link. Contrary to what the wording suggests, the criterion does not generate any insight into the service the transport system provides to the actual user, in terms of quality of travel between real origins and real destinations, let alone into the service provided to different user groups (Martens and Hurvitz 2011). Second, a closer look at transport demand modeling reveals that transport policies are actually heavily guided by market-based distributive principles. As the term suggests, transport demand modeling, which is widely used in the industrialized world as a tool to inform decision-making about investments in transport infrastructure (e.g., Bates 2000) is about demand for transport. Following the common economic definition of demand, transport demand can be defined as a desire for transport backed by the ability to pay for it (Sullivan and Sheffrin 2003). Demand-based modeling thus reflects the distributive mechanisms of the free market, as it takes past travel behavior—i.e. revealed demand for transport—as the basis for forecasting future travel demand. In doing so, it ignores the possible existence of latent demand or of transport needs for which the existing transport system does not cater (Cass et al. 2005; Denmark 1998; Martens 2006). The consequence is that the distribution of transport infrastructure founded on demand-based modeling will, by and large, reflect the way in which money—as a dominant good—is distributed over society. Rather than creating a separate sphere around the good of accessibility, demand- based modeling does exactly the opposite. Third, when distributive criteria do play an explicit role in transport policy, they tend to address only specific issues rather than the distribution of the overarching transport good, i.e. accessibility. Examples of such distributive policies include regional redistribution of fuel taxes (Taylor and Norton 2009), the provision of public transport in low-demand areas (Hodge 1995), welfare-to-work transportation programs (Lucas 2004), and the application of universal design principles to transport systems (Audirac 2008). While distributive principles are a key element of each of these policies, the distributive arrangements fall far short of establishing a true transport sphere within which accessibility is distributed in a fair way over members of society. First, the distributive arrangements typically solve only part of the accessibility problems of the target population, e.g. in terms of the number and variety of destinations being served. Second, and more importantly, a truly distributive approach to transport would not be limited to certain target groups, transport-related revenues or transport systems only. Rather, it would focus on the overall distribution of accessibility over members of society, i.e. it would link the level of accessibility provided to one group to the accessibility levels received by other groups (cf. Preston and Rajé 2007). Thus, while the field of transport is certainly a clearly demarcated area of government intervention, and distributive concerns sometimes play a formative role in policy Transportation 123 development (e.g., Hay and Trinder 1991; Trinder et al. 1991; Langmyhr 1997), it has hardly resulted in a Walzer-like sphere around accessibility as a socially valued good. This stands in sharp contrast to goods like health and education, around which, in many countries over the course of the twentieth century, Walzer-like spheres have been created to guarantee that the distribution of those goods is not shaped primarily by the distribution of money or power. Transport as a separate sphere The conclusion that the policy field of transport has not created a Walzer-like sphere around accessibility as a good, still leaves open the question whether accessibility should be singled out and a separate sphere created to guarantee a certain level of autonomy in the distribution of accessibility. Two lines can assist in answering this question. The first focuses on the value of the transport good in current societies, while the second explores the way in which the transport good defined as accessibility is currently distributed over members of society. There can be no discussion that the social meaning of transport has changed tremen- dously over the past two centuries (e.g., Knowles 2006). In traditional societies, transport was primarily a matter of walking. Space was organized around the particularities of transport by foot, with necessities of life located within walking distance of most homes (Mumford 1961). Only a small segment of society could afford regular travel by horse or horse-drawn carriages. The near-universal ability to walk—with the exception of small infants and the disabled—implied that accessibility, at least to everyday destinations, was possible for all, although in many cities regulations and social codes de facto curtailed accessibility levels for e.g. women or lower classes (Muellner 2002; Braidotti 1994). Thus, while accessibility levels will have differed between people, depending on the exact res- idential location of a person within the city (walls) and vis-à-vis key land uses like the central market place, the dominance of walking guaranteed minimal accessibility levels for all and relatively small differences in these levels, at least to everyday destinations. The introduction of motorized transport for movement of people, but especially the ascent of private, individualized, motorized transport, changed the situation fundamentally (e.g., Illich 1974). The widespread availability of the motorcar, triggered by vast invest- ments in the road system, implied a fundamental shift in the meaning of transport. The dominance of the motorcar resulted in a vast dispersal of urban functions over space, eliminating walking as a feasible alternative for most trips. As a result, motorized transport changed rapidly from a luxury into a necessity—few people in industrialized societies are now able to manage their daily lives without, individualized or collective, motorized transport. Mobility became a structuring dimension of social life (Kaufmann et al. 2004; Urry 2000). The rise of motorized transport has thus re-shaped the social meaning of the transport good. Once, transport was hardly perceived as a good, but rather taken-for-granted, as a natural extension of life itself. Now, the ability to travel through space has become so important for everyday lives, that mobility can be considered an asset. Kaufmann et al. (2004) even consider mobility—or motility as they term it—a form of capital, that may form links with, and can be exchanged for, other forms of capital, whether economic, cultural or social in shape. The availability or in-availability of transport, in other words, shapes people’s life opportunities. It is this interrelationship that shapes the social meaning of transport in today’s industrialized societies. Transportation 123 The second line of argumentation that can provide ammunition for the qualification of transport as a separate distributive sphere, relates to the way in which transport is currently distributed over members of society. The aim of the paper is not to provide a full overview of these distributive patterns (see Schweitzer and Valenzuela 2004), but rather to point at patterns and tendencies in industrialized societies. These tendencies can be derived from various strands of literature, including the spatial mismatch literature, which addresses the interrelationship between decentralization of employment and job accessibility of low- income residents; studies on transport and gender, which explore the problems of women to access work and combine multiple tasks in a spatially fragmented environment; and the more recent body of work on transport and social exclusion, which has added a more qualitative picture of the accessibility problems experienced by mobility deprived groups like the (urban) poor, ethnic minorities, children and the elderly. Taken together, these strands of research draw a picture of how the lack of motility limits the possibilities for personal accumulation of economic and social capital, to paraphrase the words of Kauf- mann et al. (2004). The spatial mismatch literature, for instance, has generated substantial evidence that the concentration of low income groups in central cities, the decentralization of low wage jobs, and the lack of investment in new public transport facilities, have in combination led to a sharp decline in job access among the urban poor (e.g., Ihlanfeldt 1993; Ong and Miller 2005). The literature on women and transport provides insight into the mobility problems experienced by women combining multiple tasks, especially if they do not own and operate a car (e.g., Blumenberg 2004). The social exclusion literature draws a qualitative picture of the everyday transport dilemmas faced by deprived popu- lation groups: the decisions to forgo a doctor’s appointment, a meeting with family and friends, a job interview, or even a full-fledged job opportunity, due to lack of adequate transport means. By doing so, this literature also highlights the intricate relationship between lack of mobility and the wider process of social exclusion (e.g., Cass et al. 2005; Hine and Mitchell 2001; Lucas 2004). Taken together, I claim that a strong case can be made for the recognition of transport as a separate distributional sphere. Transport has developed from a taken-for-granted and hardly disputed good, to a highly desirable good, an indispensable resource shaping one’s life path, and a good whose availability is subject of public debate. Furthermore, current policy arrangements allow the distribution of transport to be dominated by the availability of money, resulting in substantial inequalities between population groups and even in a lack of accessibility among a considerable part of the population. The evidence, only briefly summarized here, seems strong enough to draw boundaries around the transport good and set it apart from other goods. Towards a distributive principle for transport The recognition of transport as a separate distributive sphere raises a third question. For, if the distribution of the transport good is to be organized in a separate policy sphere, what criterion should guide the distribution of the good? Walzer’s theory provides no direct guidance here, as he upholds that the distribution of a good should be guided by internal reasons only, i.e. be derived from the social meaning a particular society ascribes to a good (see also Trappenburg 2000). Lacking a widely-shared agreement on the social meaning of the transport good, the discussion of possible distributive principles is necessarily an open-ended one. The explorations below start from the conceptualization of transport as accessibility. By critically reflecting on the applicability of a number of widely used and Transportation 123 defended distributive principles to the distribution of accessibility, some progress may be booked. The goal is not to reach a final understanding, but at least to reach beyond a mere overview of possible criteria (see e.g., Hay 1995; Khisty 1996; Langmyhr 1997). The arguments brought to the fore will be eclectic, drawing as much on the particular nature of the transport good as on moral reasoning and theories of justice. As mentioned above, for reasons of simplicity, the analysis below is developed from the viewpoint of the policy-maker(s) responsible for decisions regarding investments in (public) transport infrastructure and services. Obviously, investments in infrastructure are only one possibility to change the distribution of accessibility over households. Accessi- bility levels may also be influenced through careful urban planning, through a spatial (re-)distribution of services, or through information and communication technologies. The distributive criterion defended below might also be applied to these types of government interventions in households’ accessibility levels, although it may require a further devel- opment of the criterion. Furthermore, it needs to be noted that the impact of transport infrastructure provision on accessibility levels is not a straightforward matter, as changes in accessibility levels are often accompanied by changes in travel patterns and, in the longer run, by changes in land use, both of which can have substantial impacts on accessibility levels (e.g., Hansen 1959). Due to feedback mechanisms between transport and land use, improvements in accessi- bility levels for a large share of the population may actually result in decreasing acces- sibility levels for other, often marginalized, groups (Baeten et al. 1997). The analysis below abstracts from these dynamics and, for reasons of simplicity, assumes that the impacts of new transport facilities on accessibility levels can be assessed in a relatively straightforward way. In line with much of the social justice literature, I start my exploration of possible justice principles to guide the distribution of accessibility with the criterion of equality. Equality refers to a situation in which a good is distributed evenly over people, irrespective of the differences between those people. As Smith (1994) and others (e.g., Kolm 1996) have argued, the challenge for scholars of social justice is to provide convincing arguments why to deviate from the criterion of equality. Lacking such arguments, equality remains as the correct way to distribute a good. However, a strong argument can be put forward against the distribution of accessibility based on the principle of equality. Experiments carried out as early as the 1920s have pointed out that even if starting from an even distribution of opportunities over space, centers will develop over time as a consequence of the advantages connected to spatial proximity (e.g., Puu 2005). In other words, space by its very nature is divided into center and periphery. As a result, inequality in accessibility is inevitable. Transport policies cannot correct the differences between center and periphery; they would at best redefine the relationship between them. The principle of equality, in short, is hardly suited to guide the distribution of the transport good if defined as accessibility. The principle of desert or merit is a second, widely defended, distributive criterion. Sadurski (1985, p. 134) distinguishes three elements of merit: it is always related to a burden; it is related to a moral judgment of the actions of someone (and therefore fun- damentally different from entitlement); and it is related to past actions. The principle of merit has especially been applied to the distribution of income, as it provides the moral foundation for linking income to work (as a burden) rather than other criteria (such as need or equality). For our purposes, the question is to what extent the principle of merit could be applied to the field of transport. What sort of burden and past action would make a person deserving of a higher accessibility level than another person? There does not seem to be an Transportation 123 obvious link between any particular burden and the provision of transport, in the same way as there exist a widely accepted link between work and income. The only link that might be made is to location choice. It could be argued, for instance, that a person willing to accept the ‘burden’ of a high-density neighborhood in a central location, e.g. in terms of pollution levels or mortgage payments, is more deserving of a high accessibility level, than a person opting to live in a low-rise, suburban, neighborhood. But much can be brought against this argument. For instance, to what extent is residential location a matter of choice? To what extent is inner city living truly a burden? And, if it is, to what extent is transport an appropriate reward for the burdens of inner-city life? The link between location as a ‘burden’ and transport availability as an appropriate ‘reward’ is at best a tacit one, and hardly provides a solid basis for the distribution of transport. Another widely defended justice criterion is the principle of need (e.g., Sen 1973). This criterion, if applied to transport, would imply that individuals or groups that need higher accessibility levels than others—e.g., because they have to access more places—would also ‘receive’ more accessibility through a targeted design of transport infrastructure and additional policy measures. While the need criterion may appeal to some, its application to the field of transport is extremely problematic. The challenge is twofold: first, to distin- guish needs from wants, and, second, to translate basic needs—such as the need for food or health—into travel needs. The first is an extremely touchy subject, although the literature on basic needs can provide guidance (e.g., Doyal and Gough 1991; Braybrooke 1987). The second is extremely precarious given the fact that it has become increasingly problematic to relate needs to well-defined travel needs to ‘‘pre-defined ‘public’ goods and services located within pre-determined ‘formal’ locations/destinations’’ (Cass et al. 2005, p. 551). Cass et al. actually argue that the increasing importance of social networks in maintaining a ‘good life’ has resulted in a dispersed pattern of travel needs that can hardly be captured through regular transport analysis. But even if these problems could be solved, a more practical barrier for the application of the need criterion to the transport field remains. This barrier is a result of the fact that transport infrastructure and services are provided to collectives rather than individuals, and for the long-term rather than the short-term. As a result, the current needs of individuals are of little relevance in the provision of transport facilities. The needs of collectives, such as neighborhoods, now and in the future, are what counts. Since population structures of neighborhoods can and will change over time, the consequence would be that near identical levels of transport service would have to be provided to each and every neighborhood. Hence, our conclusion is that the criterion of need lacks distinctive force to guide the distribution of the transport good (see also Apparicio and Seguin 2006). The last two distributive principles have in common that they relate the distribution to the characteristics of a person, i.e. burdens or needs. Another set of principles does not take these characteristics into account, but rather distributes a good in an arithmetic way. Rawls, in his ‘A Theory of Justice’, suggests that at least four such principles should be discussed between the individuals placed behind his famous veil of ignorance (Rawls 1971; see also Frohlich and Oppenheimer 1992): maximizing the average income; maximizing the average income with a floor constraint for the minimum; maximizing the average income with a range constraint; and maximizing the lowest income (Rawls’ difference principle). Each of these principles could be easily transposed to the field of transport, by replacing the word ‘income’ with ‘accessibility’. While Rawls by no means argued that his approach could or should be transposed to specific policy fields (see Blocker and Smith 1980), for the purpose of the paper it is useful to explore the applicability of these four principles to the distribution of accessibility. The question here is, whether each or any of the principles Transportation 123 could serve as a guiding principle for the transport sphere. When looking at the options, the first of these criteria (maximizing the average accessibility level) seems to be of little relevance, as it hardly guides the actual distribution of the transport good over population groups. Rawls’ difference principle (maximizing the lowest level), in turn, also has its problems when applied to accessibility. Rawls developed this criterion for income, based on the understanding that differences in income might result in a better working economy, which would then, in turn, generate a higher level of income for the worst-off. The question is if a comparable mechanism could be at work in transport, i.e. whether by allowing differences in accessibility the whole transport system would perform better, thereby generating a higher accessibility level for the worst-off. The argument seems at best far-fetched and surely falls far short of providing a practical criterion to guide dis- tribution in the transport sphere. This brief analysis of possible distributive criteria suggests that two potential principles remain as possibly relevant for the field of transport: (1) maximizing the average acces- sibility level with a floor constraint for the minimum; and (2) maximizing the average accessibility level with a range constraint. The difference between these two principles is a qualitative one; the second criterion simply defines the height of the floor constraint in relation to the maximal accessibility level experienced by the best-off person. In case the second criterion is employed in policy making, the floor constraint will be automatically adjusted in accordance with changing accessibility levels. The first criterion lacks such an adaptive mechanism, implying that the floor constraint will have to be re-assessed whenever substantial changes in accessibility levels occur across-the-board. Following these latter observations the so-called ‘maximax’ criterion for the distribution of accessibility has been defined. The criterion combines the goal of maximum average accessibility with a limit on the maximal gap allowed between the worst-off and the best-off in terms of accessibility levels. The application of the maximax principle in transport planning and policy would assist decision-makers in the selection of transport projects that maximize average accessibility levels, while ensuring that the accessibility gaps between population groups remain within an acceptable range (Fig. 3). In comparison to the equality principle, the maximax criterion does not demand uniformity and is thus in line with the inevitable differences in accessibility created by space. And in comparison to the need criterion, the maximax principle does not require a paternalistic approach in which transport institutions rather than people themselves determine which trips count as ‘needs’ and which as ‘wants’. Given these features, the maximax principle seems to be a practically applicable principle to guide the distribution of the transport good within a separate distributive sphere. Note that maximum average accessibility not necessarily implies maximum mobility, as accessibility can also be achieved through e.g. land use interventions. It neither has to imply an increase in accessibility levels across-the-board, as the requirement to limit accessibility gaps up to a certain maximum may well imply policies that increase accessibility levels for some at the expense of the (high) accessibility levels of others. It may be clear that the suggested distributive approach, and the application of the maximax principle, would have profound implications for transportation planning. It would imply a shift from a systems approach to the transport network, as is common today, to a systematic assessment of the accessibility gaps between the transport disadvantaged and those groups in society that experience the highest accessibility levels. The application of the maximax principle would require policy makers to guarantee that these gaps do not exceed a pre-defined threshold. Whenever the threshold would be exceeded, as might be the case for e.g. car-less households in certain ‘pockets’ of the urban region, transport investment priorities would have to be set so that the gaps in accessibility levels would be Transportation 123 reduced to the pre-defined level of acceptance. In practice, this might imply, for example, investing in a system of bus lines and lanes that serves deprived neighborhoods, rather than in a new railway line or highway extension that alleviates a highly congested corridor. Conclusion In this paper, I have sought to apply the ideas of Walzer to the field of transport. Walzer maintains that justice is a matter of fences, fences between spheres in which goods with distinct social meanings are being distributed solely on the basis of criteria that are relevant for those goods. I have argued that, given the distinct meaning of transport in current societies, as well as the emerging gaps in its distribution, transport ‘deserves’ its own distributive sphere. The establishment of such a sphere would ensure that the distribution of accessibility over people will be guided by a deliberate distributive policy, rather than strongly shaped by the distribution of money. I have subsequently explored what kind of justice principle could guide the distribution of the transport good, defined as accessibility, once a separate sphere would be established. This preliminary exploration has resulted in the elimination of a number of widely supported distributive principles, and in the tentative identification of a criterion that seems to match the particularities of the transport good. Many issues still remain. First, for reasons of simplicity, the explorations in the paper have been based on a simplified, static, perspective on the land use–transport interaction. A proper distributive perspective to transport defined as accessibility will have to take into account the inherently dynamic interplay between changes in accessibility levels and land use patterns. It also will have to take into consideration the notion of choice, e.g. the fact that people may trade-off higher levels of accessibility against e.g. lower housing costs, and its consequences for the way in which gaps in accessibility levels should be assessed. Furthermore, the definition of transport as accessibility requires a broader conceptuali- zation of government intervention, to include e.g. service delivery policies and ICT range + 0range constraint do nothing scenario a cc e ss ib ili ty le ve l highest accessibility level average lowest accessibility level range + 1 le ve l o f a cc e ss highest accessibility level average lowest accessibility level range + 0 le ve l o f a cc e ss highest accessibility level average lowest accessibility level le ve l o f a cc e ss highest accessibility level average lowest accessibility level scenario a scenario b scenario c Fig. 3 Example application of the maximax principle. The diagrams depict the impact of four alternative infrastructure investments on the distribution of accessibility over households. The left-hand diagram describes the situation at t1 for the do-nothing scenario. As in case of regular cost-benefit analysis, this scenario is used as the base line against which to compare alternative investment scenarios. Note that the do-nothing scenario exactly satisfies the range constraint in accessibility level between the worst-off and best-off, as set by policy makers. Scenario A depicts a situation in which accessibility levels are improved across-the-board: both the worst-off and best-off experience an improvement in accessibility, while the average accessibility level also increases. However, following the maximax principle, this scenario has to be rejected as the gap between the best-off and the worst-off exceeds the range constraint set by policy makers (as indicated by ‘range ? 1’ in the diagram). Scenarios B and C both satisfy the range constraint and can therefore be considered as possible investments strategies. The choice between these scenarios and the do- nothing scenario is subsequently made through a comparison of the average accessibility level in each scenario. Scenario C results in a substantially higher average accessibility level than scenario B or the do- nothing scenario. Hence, scenario C is to be preferred, despite the fact that it results in a lower accessibility level for both the worst-off and the best-off household than scenario B Transportation 123 measures. Also, the defended maximax principle, and the underlying indicator of acces- sibility levels, will have to be operationalized, so that its value can be assessed in practical case studies. Finally, and perhaps most importantly, the proposed distributive approach to transport will have far-reaching consequences for the institutional framework of transport planning, perhaps comparable to those generated by proposed schemes for personal carbon rationing (see e.g. Fawcett 2004), which will have to be explored and addressed. For these and other reasons, the paper hardly provides final answers to its central questions. Rather, it should be viewed as the opening of an (explicit) debate about the social meaning of the transport good in current hyper-mobile societies, the need for an explicit distributive transport policy, and the distributive principle that should guide such a policy. Acknowledgments The paper is the result of a larger research project into justice and transport funded by the Volvo Research and Educational Foundations. Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License which permits any use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author(s) and the source are credited. References Altshuler, A.: The Urban Transportation System. MIT Press, Cambridge (1979) Apparicio, P., Seguin, A.-M.: Measuring the accessibility of services and facilities for residents of public housing in Montreal. Urban Stud. 43, 187–211 (2006) Audirac, I.: Accessing transit as universal design. J. Plan. Lit. 23, 4–16 (2008) Baeten, G., Spithoven, A., Albrechts, L.: Mobiliteit: landschap van macht en onmacht. Acco, Leuven (1997) Bates, J.: History of demand modelling. In: Hensher, D.A., Button, K.J. (eds.) Handbook of Transport Modelling, pp. 11–34. Pergamon, Oxford (2000) Beatley, T.: Equity and distributional issues in infrastructure planning: a theoretical perspective. In: Stein, J.M. (ed.) Public Infrastructure Planning and Management, pp. 208–226. Sage, Newbury Park (1988) Benenson, I., Martens, K., Rofe, Y.: Measuring the gap between car and transit accessibility: estimating access using a high-resolution transit network geographic information system. Transp. Res. Rec. J. Transp. Res. Board 2144, 28–35 (2010) Bergman, S., Sager, T.: The ethics of mobilities: rethinking place, exclusion, freedom and environment, p. 275. Ashgate, Aldershot (2008) Bertolini, L., le Clercq, F., Kapoen, L.: Sustainable accessibility: a conceptual framework to integrate transport and land use plan-making. Two test-applications in the Netherlands and a reflection on the way forward. Transp. Policy 12, 207–220 (2005) Black, J., Conroy, M.: Accessibility measures and the social evaluation of urban structure. Environ. Plan. A 9, 1013–1031 (1977) Blocker, H.G., Smith, E.H.: John Rawls’ Theory of Social Justice: An Introduction. Ohio University Press, Athens (1980) Blumenberg, E.A.: Engendering effective planning: spatial mismatch, low-income women, and transpor- tation policy. J. Am. Plan. Assoc. 70, 269–281 (2004) Braidotti, R.: Nomadic Subjects: Embodiment and Sexual Difference in Contemporary Feminist Theory. Columbia University Press, New York (1994) Braybrooke, D.: Meeting Needs. Princeton University Press, Princeton (1987) Bröcker, J., Korzhenevych, A., Schürmann, C.: Assessing spatial equity and efficiency impacts of transport infrastructure projects. Transp. Res. B 44, 795–811 (2010) Cass, N., Shove, E., Urry, J.: Social exclusion, mobility and access. Sociol. Rev. 53, 539–555 (2005) Cervero, R.: Efficiency and equity impacts of current transit fare policies. Transp. Res. Rec. J. Transp. Res. Board 799, 7–15 (1981) Cervero, R., Neil, J.S., Paul, B.B.: Transportation planning. In: International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, pp. 15873–15878. Pergamon, Oxford (2001) Couclelis, H.: The death of distance. Environ. Plan. B 23, 387–389 (1996) Transportation 123 Cresswell, T.: The right to mobility: the production of mobility in the courtroom. Antipode 38, 735–754 (2006) Daniels, N.: Just Health: Meeting Health Needs Fairly. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2008) de Dios Ortuzar, J., Willumsen, L.G.: Modelling Transport, 3rd edn. Wiley, Chichester (2001) Denmark, D.: The outsiders: planning and transport disadvantage. J. Plan. Educ. Res. 17, 231–245 (1998) Dijst, M.: Het elliptisch leven: actieruimte als integrale maat voor bereik en mobiliteit. Koninklijk Nederlands Aardrijkskundig Genootschap/Faculteit Bouwkunde Technische Universiteit Delft, Utrecht/Delft (1995) Dong, X., Ben-Akiva, M.E., Bowman, J.L., Walker, J.L.: Moving from trip-based to activity-based measures of accessibility. Transp. Res. A 40, 163–180 (2006) Doyal, L., Gough, I.: A Theory of Human Need. The Macmillan Press, Houndsmill (1991) Dworkin, R.: Reply to Michael Walzer. The New York Review of Books, 30 (1983a) Dworkin, R.: To each his own. The New York Review of Books, 30 (1983b) Ecola, L., Light, T.: Equity and congestion pricing: a review of the evidence. Rand Corporation, Santa Monica (2009) Fabre, C.: Justice in a Changing World. Polity Press, Cambridge (2007) Farrington, J., Farrington, C.: Rural accessibility, social inclusion and social justice: towards conceptuali- sation. J. Transp. Geogr. 13, 1–12 (2005) Fawcett, T.: Carbon rationing and personal energy use. Energy Environ. 15, 1067–1084 (2004) Feitelson, E.: Introducing environmental equity dimensions into the sustainable transport discourse: issues and pitfalls. Transp. Res. D 7, 99–118 (2002) Forkenbrock, D.J., Schweitzer, L.A.: Environmental justice in transportation planning. J. Am. Plan. Assoc. 65, 96–111 (1999) Frohlich, N., Oppenheimer, J.A.: Choosing Justice: An Experimental Approach to Ethical Theory. Uni- versity of California Press, Berkeley (1992) Garb, Y., Levine, J.: Congestion pricing’s conditional promise: promotion of accessibility or mobility? Transp. Policy 9, 179–188 (2002) Garrett, M., Taylor, B.: Reconsidering social equity in public transit. Berkeley Plan. J. 13, 6–27 (1999) Hansen, W.G.: How accessibility shapes land use. J. Am. Inst. Planners 25, 73–76 (1959) Harvey, D.: The Condition of Postmodernity: An Enquiry into the Origins of Cultural Change. Blackwell, Malden (1990) Hay, A.M.: Concepts of equity, fairness and justice in geographical studies. Trans. Inst. Br. Geogr. 20, 500–508 (1995) Hay, A.M., Trinder, E.: Concepts of equity, fairness, and justice expressed by local transport policymakers. Environ. Plan. C 9, 453–465 (1991) Hess, D.B.: Access to employment for adults in poverty in the Buffalo–Niagara region. Urban Stud. 42, 1177–1200 (2005) Hine, J.P., Mitchell, F.: Better for everyone? Travel experiences and transport exclusion. Urban Stud. Special Issue on ‘The barrier free city: possibilities and prospects’ edited by R. Imrie 38, 319 (2001) Hodge, D.C.: Fiscal equity in urban mass transit systems: a geographical analysis. Ann. Assoc. Am. Geogr. 78, 288–306 (1988) Hodge, D.C.: My fair share: equity issues in urban transportation. In: Hanson, S. (ed.) The Geography of Urban Transportation, 2nd edn. The Guilford Press, New York (1995) Ihlanfeldt, K.: Intra-urban job accessibility and hispanic youth employment rates. J. Urban Econ. 33, 254–271 (1993) Illich, I.: Energy and Equity. Marion Boyars, London (1974) Kaufmann, V.: Re-Thinking Mobility: Contemporary Sociology. Ashgate, Aldershot (2002) Kaufmann, V., Bergman, M.M., Joye, D.: Motility: mobility as capital. Int. J. Urban Reg. Res. 28, 745–756 (2004) Kawabata, M., Shen, Q.: Commuting inequality between cars and public transit: the case of the San Francisco Bay area, 1990–2000. Urban Stud. 44, 1759–1780 (2007) Khisty, C.J.: Operationalizing concepts of equity for public project investments. Transp. Res. Rec. J. Transp. Res. Board 1559, 94–99 (1996) Khisty, C.J., Zeitler, U.: Is hypermobility a challenge for transport ethics and systemicity? Syst. Pract. Action Res. 1, 597–613 (2001) Knowles, R.D.: Transport shaping space: differential collapse in time–space. J. Transp. Geogr. 14, 407–425 (2006) Kolm, S.-C.: Modern Theories of Justice. MIT Press, Cambridge (1996) Kwan, M.-P.: Space–time and integral measures of individual accessibility: a comparative analysis using a point-based framework. Geogr. Anal. 30, 191–216 (1998) Transportation 123 Kwan, M.-P.: Gender and individual access to urban opportunities: a study using space–time measures. Prof. Geogr. 51, 210–227 (1999) Kwan, M.-P.: Gender differences in space–time constraints. Area 32, 145–156 (2000) Kwan, M.-P., Hong, X.-D.: Network-based constraints-oriented choice set formation using GIS. Geogr. Inf. 5, 139–162 (1998) Langmyhr, T.: Managing equity: the case of road pricing. Transp. Policy 4, 25–39 (1997) Lomasky, L.E.: Autonomy and automobility. Indep. Rev. v.II, 5–28 (1997) Lucas, K.: Running on Empty: Transport, Social Exclusion and Environmental Justice. Policy Press, Bristol (2004) Lucy, W.H.: Equity and planning for local services. J. Am. Plan. Assoc. 47, 447–457 (1981) Lucy, W.H.: Equity planning for infrastructure: applications. In: Stein, J.M. (ed.) Public Infrastructure Planning and Management, pp. 227–240. Sage, Newbury Park (1988) Martens, K.: Basing Transport Planning on Principles of Social Justice. Berkeley Plan. J. 19, 1–17 (2006) Martens, K.: Substance precedes methodology: on cost-benefit analysis and equity. Transportation 38(6), 959–974 (2011) Martens, K., Golub, A.: A justice-theoretic exploration of accessibility measures. In: Geurs, K.T., Krizek, K.J. (eds.) Accessibility and Transport Planning: Challenges for Europe and North America. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham (in press) Martens, K., Hurvitz, E.: Distributive impacts of demand-based modelling. Transportmetrica 7, 181–200 (2011) Miller, H.J.: Place-based versus people-based geographic information science. Geogr. Compass 1, 503–535 (2007) Miranda, R., Tunyavong, I.: Patterned inequality? Reexamining the role of distributive politics in urban service delivery. Urban Aff. Q. 29, 509–534 (1994) Muellner, B.: The deviance of respectability: nineteenth-century transport from a woman’s perspective. J. Transp. Hist. 23, 37–45 (2002) Mumford, L.: The City in History: Its Origins, Its Transformations, and Its Prospects. Harcourt, Brace & World, New York (1961) Murray, A.T., Davis, R.: Equity in regional service provision. J. Reg. Sci. 41, 577–600 (2001) Neutens, T., Schwanen, T., Witlox, F., De Maeyer, P.: Equity of urban service delivery: a comparison of different accessibility measures. Environ. Plan. A 42, 1613–1635 (2010a) Neutens, T., Schwanen, T., Witlox, F., De Maeyer, P.: Evaluating the temporal organization of public service provision using space–time accessibility analysis. Urban Geogr. 31, 1039–1064 (2010b) Niemeier, D.A.: Accessibility: an evaluation using consumer welfare. Transportation 24, 377–396 (1997) Ong, P.M., Miller, D.: Spatial and transportation mismatch in Los Angeles. J. Plan. Educ. Res. 25, 43–56 (2005) Pirie, G.H.: Measuring accessibility: a review and proposal. Environ. Plan. A 11, 299–312 (1979) Preston, J., Rajé, F.: Accessibility, mobility and transport-related social exclusion. J. Transp. Geogr. 15, 151–160 (2007) Puu, T.: On the genesis of hexagonal shapes. Netw. Spatial Econ. 5, 5–20 (2005) Rawls, J.: A Theory of Justice. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (1971) Richardson, H.W.: A note on the distributional effects of road pricing. J. Transp. Econ. Policy 8, 82–85 (1974) Rimmer, P.: Transport geography. Prog. Hum. Geogr. 9, 271–277 (1985) Rucker, G.: Public transportation: another gap in rural America. Transp. Q. 38, 419–432 (1984) Sadurski, W.: Giving Desert Its Due: Social Justice and Legal Theory. D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht (1985) Sager, T.: Footloose and forecast-free: hypermobility and the planning of society. Eur. J. Spatial Dev. September 2005, 1–23 (2005) Schweitzer, L., Stephenson, M.: Right answers, wrong questions: environmental justice as urban research. Urban Stud. 44, 319–337 (2007) Schweitzer, L., Valenzuela, A.: Environmental injustice and transportation: the claims and the evidence. J. Plan. Lit. 18, 383–398 (2004) Sen, A.K.: On Economic Inequality. Clarendon Press, Oxford (1973) Smeed, R.J.: Road Pricing: The Economic and Technical Possibilities. HMSO, London (1964) Smith, D.M.: Geography and Social Justice. Blackwell, Cambridge (1994) Sullivan, A., Sheffrin, S.M.: Economics: Principles in Action. Pearson Prentice Hall, Upper Saddle River (2003) Talen, E.: Access: geographical. Int. Encycl. Soc. Behav. Sci. 1, 30–33 (2001) Transportation 123 Talen, E., Anselin, L.: Assessing spatial equity: an evaluation of measures of accessibility to public play- grounds. Environ. Plan. A 30, 595–613 (1998) Taylor, B.D., Norton, A.T.: Paying for transportation: what’s a fair price? J. Plan. Lit. 24, 22–36 (2009) Teuber, A.: Bookreview of spheres of justice by Michael Walzer. Political Theory 12, 118–123 (1984) Trappenburg, M.: In defence of pure pluralism: two readings of Walzer’s spheres of justice. J. Polit. Philos. 8, 343–362 (2000) Trinder, E., Hay, A.M., Dignan, J., Else, P., Skorupski, J.: Concepts of equity, fairness and justice in British transport legislation, 1960–1988. Environ. Plan. C 9, 31–50 (1991) Urry, J.: Sociology Beyond Societies: Mobilities for the Twenty First Century. Routledge, London (2000) Van Wee, B.: Transport and Ethics: Ethics and the Evaluation of Transport Policies and Projects. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham (2011) Vigar, G.: Transport for people: accessibility, mobility and equity in transport planning. In: Greed, C.H. (ed.) Social Town Planning, pp. 90–101. Routledge, London (1999) Wachs, M., Kumagai, T.G.: Physical accessibility as a social indicator. Socio-Econ. Plan. Sci. 6, 357–379 (1973) Walzer, M.: Spheres of Justice: A Defense of Pluralism and Equality. Basic Books, New York (1983) Walzer, M.: Response. In: Miller, D., Walzer, M. (eds.) Pluralism, Justice, and Equality, pp. 281–296. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1995) Wu, B.M., Hine, J.P.: A PTAL approach to measuring changes in bus service accessibility. Transp. Policy 10, 307–320 (2003) Young, I.M.: Justice and the Politics of Difference. Princeton University Press, Princeton (1990) Zeitler, U.: Grundlagen der Verkehrsethik. Logos Verlag, Berlin (1999) Author Biography Karel Martens is an assistant professor at the Institute for Management Research, Radboud University Nijmegen, the Netherlands. His main research interests include transport and justice, the land use–transport interrelationship, parking, and multi-modal transportation. He has published and presented a number of papers on transport and justice, among others in Transportation (2011), Transportmetrica (2011, with co- author), The Annals of Regional Science (2010, with co-authors), Transportation Research Records (2010, with co-authors), Berkeley Planning Journal (2006), and at the Annual Conference of the Transportation Research Board (2007, 2009, 2011). Transportation 123 Justice in transport as justice in accessibility: applying Walzer’s ‘Spheres of Justice’ to the transport sector Abstract Introduction Walzer’s Spheres of Justice The social meaning of the transport good Transportation as a field of policy intervention Transport as a separate sphere Towards a distributive principle for transport Conclusion Acknowledgments References work_3a5wf45pobc3neqiawkkny223i ---- Microsoft Word - Hosseini.docx Vol. 6, No. 9, 2017 DOI: 10.22099/JPS.2017.4965, ISSN: 2322-2557 pp. 101-103   William Shakespeare’s Sonnets. Translated by Omid Tabibzadeh. Tehran: Niloofar Publishers, 2017. 411 pp. ISBN 978-964-448-712-5 (hardback) Mostafa Hosseini Bu-Ali Sina University Hamedan, Iran hosseiny.mostafa1352@gmail.com Without question, William Shakespeare (1564- 1616) occupies a unique position in the history of English literature. He wrote 37 plays, 154 sonnets and 4 narrative poems. Shakespeare’s sonnets are the most personal of his works, so it acts as a unique introduction to Shakespeare’s mindset, on the one hand, and very seminal entry for the familiarity with the manifestations of thought and literature in Renaissance England, on the other hand. Because of the importance of Shakespeare’s sonnets in English literature and, by extension, in the World literature, the lack of a complete Persian translation and interpretation necessitates this new rendering. Translation of Shakespeare’s works in Persian has a long and eventful history. As far as we know, during the Qajar Era (1785- 1925) Shakespeare’s plays began to appear in Persian costume. Hosseingholi Salvar was the first one who translated Shakespeare’s comedy The Taming of the Shrew in 1899/ 1278. Later, Abu’l-Qāsem Khān Qarāgozlu, better known as Nāṣer-al-molk, who was a Persian politician during Qajar Era, translated The Tragedy of Othello, the Moor 102                         Persian Literary Studies Journal   of Venice which came out in 1961/1339 in France. Fortunately, from that time onwards, the translation of Shakespeare’s plays continues up to the present time. Unlike Shakespeare’s plays that some of them (e.g. Hamlet, Macbeth, Othello, King Lear, and Romeo and Juliet) have been translated over and over again, Persian translators have not paid much attention to Shakespeare’s poems. From Shakespeare’s narrative poems just Venus and Adonis and The Rape of Lucrece have been translated into Persian respectively in 1301/1922 and 1335/1956. It is worth mentioning that Lotfali Suratgar, a professor of English and comparative literature at the University of Tehran, was the first person who produced a Persian version of these two long narrative poems. Unluckily, the former remained unfinished. The credit for translating Shakespeare’s Sonnets in Persian is almost unanimously given to Iranian poet and translator, Masoud Farzad. Presumably, he translated five of Shakespeare’s sonnets into prose between 1933/1312 and 1938/1317. In addition to scattered prose and verse translations of Shakespeare’s sonnets, there are two selected bilingual translations of his sonnets: one in prose, including 100 sonnets, by Taghi Tafazzoli (1998/ 1377), and the other in verse, including 78 sonnets, by Behnam Moghddam (2000/1370). But translating a collection of Shakespeare’s Sonnets cannot provoke the same sense in the reader as that of the whole cycle. Although each of these sonnets is independent, they are thematically linked. Omid Tabibzadeh’s recent translation is the first complete translation of Shakespeare’s Sonnets into Persian. The volume includes all the 154 sonnets, features a long, informative, and path-breaking introduction, and helpful glosses. Providing information on the genre, English sonnet, and Shakespeare’s Sonnets, the “Introduction” is long and informative. Discussions include the dedication of Thorpe’s 1609 edition, the 1940 pirated edition of the sonnets by John Benson, their order and date of composition and autobiographical contents. Selection of medium and form are among critical decisions for translating poetry. Tabibzadeh has rendered Shakespeare’s Sonnets into lucid and fluent Persian prose. Also, he has done his best to keep Shakespeare’s brevity of WILLIAM SHAKESPEARE’S SONNETS 103 language, that is, for each line in English there is exactly one line in Persian. All in all, it is a successful translation with sporadic flourishes of lyricism. The third section is the most informative part of the book as it is impossible to have a deep understanding of Shakespeare’s Sonnets without explanatory notes, because they are replete with political and social references, mythological and biblical allusions, and literal devices e.g. puns, double entendres, and word plays. In my opinion, it is the translator’s towering achievement. To do this, he has consulted the most authentic and up to date sources written by seminal Shakespeare-scholars, e.g. Thomas George Tucker and Katherine Duncan-Jones. Despite all these merits, the book has also its drawbacks. One, for some proper nouns there are different Persian pronunciations (e.g. in p. 40 « و » چاپمن چپمن« » for Chapman; and in p. 293 « دان«و » داون » for Donne. A more vigorous copyediting would have reduced typographical errors like “sonett” instead of “sonetto” (34); and «باربينگ» instead of «30) «بربيج). The translation also fails to notice multiple meanings in some words and phrases including “princes” (170), l.2; “black lines” in p.186, l.13; and “O Cunning Love” in p.356, l.13). Some mythological references are also missed (e. g. p. 98, l.2 “Devouring Time” refers to the myth of Coronus; and p.162, l.8 “winged speed” refers to the myth of Pegasus). Five, according to dictionaries of quotations some lines and phrases from Shakespeare’s Sonnets have passed into the common stock of English proverbial expression and cliché. Unfortunately, this part is totally missed in the present book. Despite these criticisms, Tabibzadeh should be complimented for offering this charming translation, together with his comprehensive analysis of the Sonnets. work_3ejmeuhvd5ffrasw7ui7em4fuu ---- The Quest for Transitional Justice in Afghanistan: Exploring the Untapped Potential of Customary Justice JOURNAL FÜR ENTWICKLUNGSPOLITIK herausgegeben vom Mattersburger Kreis für Entwicklungspolitik an den österreichischen Universitäten vol. XXVII 3–2011 Beyond Transitional Justice Schwerpunktredaktion: Stefan Khittel Inhaltsverzeichnis 4 Stefan Khittel, Jan Pospisil Beyond Transitional Justice? 21 Sandra Rubli Knowing the Truth – What For? The Contested Politics of Transitional Justice in Burundi 43 Susanne Schmeidl The Quest for Transitional Justice in Afghanistan: Exploring the Untapped Potential of Customary Justice 64 Katja Seidel Practising Justice in Argentina: Social Condemnation, Legal Punishment, and the Local Articulations of Genocide 88 Christian Wlaschütz Transitional Justice in Colombia: Does it Contribute to Reconciliation? 109 Book Review 111 Editor of the Special Issue and Authors 114 Impressum The Quest for Transitional Justice in Afghanistan Journal für Entwicklungspolitik XXVII 3-2011, S. 43-63 SUSANNE SCHMEIDL The Quest for Transitional Justice in Afghanistan: Exploring the Untapped Potential of Customary Justice1 1. Introduction The quest for peace in Afghanistan has been a long one. The country has endured several cycles of war over the past 30 plus years. The most recent attempt at building peace started in 2001, with the now some- what infamous ‘Agreement on Provisional Arrangements in Afghanistan Pending the Re-Establishment of Permanent Government Institutions’ (Bonn Agreement). Today, nearly 10 years later, security is still elusive and it seems that Afghanistan is further away from finding peace than it was a decade ago. The Taliban has re-emerged with new strength, backed by foreign sponsor nations and benefiting from a weak and corrupt Afghan government. They are fighting a government that has lost legitimacy, because, amongst other reasons, it absorbed many jihadi personalities whose inability to agree on power sharing after the defeat of the Commu- nist government in 1992 gave rise to the first Taliban movement. What has been falling by the wayside in all these discussions about peace is the issue of reconciliation and justice. While “[t]he UN mission in Afghanistan had from the beginning been mandated to ‘promote national reconciliation and rapprochement throughout the country’ […] the Bonn conference, which was structured as a meeting of victors and set the framework for the transition period, made this role difficult” (Suhrke et al. 2009: 3). The fact that the Taliban, believed to be defeated at that time, were not party to the Bonn peace talks emphasized, even at this stage, a lack of focus on reconciliation. Backed by international supporters, the Afghan government has continued to argue that peace is more important than justice, and that dealing with past crimes and  Susanne Schmeidl those who committed them would only damage the fragile and fledgling new state. For many Afghans, history is repeating itself and there are questions as to whether the new Afghanistan Peace and Reintegration Program (APRP) will indeed be able to bring about reconciliation and peace. Until now, all government programmes on peace and reintegration – most importantly the 2007 Amnesty Bill passed by Parliament for those involved in past wars (Suhrke et al. 2009), as well as discussions about the implementation of the APRP – have implied a focus on amnesty over justice, emphasizing job creation and development projects as a way to reconcile fighters, while ignoring existing grievances, both amongst communities and some insur- gents. How can the Afghan people trust that their government is genuine in its interest in peace and reconciliation if it has once before firmly closed the door on justice for jihadi commanders, arguing that the government tent was big enough to accommodate everybody,2 regardless of their past human rights records (Wilder/Lister 2007)? The question remains this: if the Afghan government and its international supporters are unable to achieve transitional justice at a more national level, why there has been such little exploration of tapping into bottom-up approaches such as using customary justice providers to achieve some ‘dealing with the past’ at the grass-roots level? Even though, in principle, the APRP programme speaks of negotiations and addressing grievances at the community level as a first step to peace and reintegration, it remains unclear how this is to be done. Building on calls by The Liaison Office (2011a), this article explores the possibility of using customary justice mechanisms as a form of grievance resolution in order to bring peace at least at village/community level, with an effective reintegration of some medium and lower-level commanders as well as fighters. It would also lay the foundations of a bottom-up reconciliation process until political will at the national level is strong enough to develop a more formal mechanism of transitional justice. This would at a minimum address some of the calls of Afghan citizens, as expressed by one who attended a ‘ jirga for the victims of wars’ on 9 May 2010: “I want to know why they did what they did and I need them to at least admit it and apologise to the people” (Frogh 2010a). Much like Truth and Reconciliation Commissions undertaken in South Africa, working The Quest for Transitional Justice in Afghanistan with customary mechanisms, which emphasize restorative justice, would achieve some form of accountability for past crimes, even if punishment in the western sense is not forthcoming. 2. The failure of transitional justice in Afghanistan It has been argued that, in order to “substantively address the past, political will needs to be developed and political institutions will need to be involved” (Winterbotham 2010: 20). The Afghan government, however, has quite a poor track record in this regard. Despite extensive consultations by the Afghanistan Independent Human Rights Commission (AIHRC) in 2004, which found a “rich understanding of and strong desire for justice among the people for both past and current crimes” (AIHRC 2005: 41), the Afghan Government has failed to tap into such popular support for transitional justice, succumbing instead to the pressures of those within their ranks that wanted amnesty for crimes committed. While a National Action Plan for Peace, Reconciliation and Justice in Afghanistan was developed in 2005, and also included in the 2006 Afghanistan Compact and the 2008 Afghanistan National Development Strategy (ANDS), it was never implemented. “President Karzai subsequently refused a request from the Afghanistan Independent Human Rights Commission (AIHRC) and civil society groups to extend its deadline” when it expired in March 2009 (Winterbotham 2010: 18). This failure to address the legacy of impunity in Afghanistan is also visible in the rather superficial programmes to date attempting to reintegrate fighters of the past Afghan wars. In the beginning, substantial funds were poured into two programmes – Disarmament, Demobilisation and Reintegration (DDR) and Disbandment of Illegal Armed Groups (DIAG) – both implemented through the Afghan New Beginnings Program (ANBP), which focussed exclusively on mujahideen fighters and not Taliban. While high-ranking commanders were allowed to enter the political arena early on, due to their predominance at the Bonn talks and subsequent support from the Afghan President, lower level fighters were not always successfully reintegrated into Afghan society. Some even argue that the recent proliferation of community  Susanne Schmeidl militias, such as in Afghanistan’s North, is ample evidence of the failure of DDR and DIAG and the fact that many former jihadi commanders simply lacked prospects in a peaceful Afghanistan and so once again took up arms for personal gain (Schmeidl/Miszak 2011). The first national programme focussing on reintegrating Taliban fighters, the Proceay-e Tahkeem-e Solha (PTS), or National Commission for Peace and Reconciliation, was established in 2005 (Suhrke et al. 2009; Waldman 2010). The programme, however, was immediately subject to wide criticism, such as that it failed to provide guarantees, that it was open to being subverted by local strongmen, that it did not provide for community involvement and, above all, that it failed to bring in genuine Taliban fighters, or at least not high ranking ones (Suhrke et al. 2009; Waldman 2010; The Liaison Office 2010b). The proposition of ‘The National Stability and Reconciliation Law’ put forth by a coalition of powerful warlords and their supporters in 2007 to Parliament in order to prevent the prosecution of individuals respon- sible for large-scale human rights abuses in the preceding decades further underscored the push for amnesty and impunity over justice. When Afghan President Hamid Karzai quietly signed this ‘Amnesty Law’ in 2010, after repeated promises that he would not support it, he finally slammed the transitional justice door firmly shut by stating that “all those who were engaged in armed conflict before the formation of the Interim Administration in Afghanistan in December 2001 shall ‘enjoy all their legal rights and shall not be prosecuted’” (Human Rights Watch 2010). Enter the new Afghanistan Peace and Reintegration Program (APRP), trying to offer a way back into society for those Taliban fighters who have tired of war or no longer see fighting as way of achieving their goals. While the programme does speak of “good governance and legitimate grievance reso- lution with assistance to subnational formal and informal governance struc- tures to promote peace, reconciliation and manage reintegration” (Islamic Republic of Afghanistan 2010: 4), the Minister of Education, Farooq Wardak “told a gathering of civil society representatives that ‘justice’ and ‘human rights’ were not on the agenda and would not be discussed” (Mojumdar 2010). Furthermore, at the 2010 Peace Jirga “[t]here was no mention of the war crimes during the civil war, nor the injustices and violence inflicted on Afghan nation in the past nine years” (Frogh 2010b: 8). The Quest for Transitional Justice in Afghanistan In light of the above, Afghan communities have developed considerable scepticism about government-led top-down reconciliation attempts, and particularly those that put government authorities in charge of reconciliation, thus dictating who would spearhead programmes (Theros/Kaldor 2011: 31). The selection of those sitting on the High Peace Council (HPC) and the Provincial Peace Committees (PPCs) that have been established in 28 of Afghanistan’s 35 provinces (Afghan Peace and Reconciliation Program 2011) only re-emphasizes a tendency to put in charge those who likely benefit most from the current status quo and continued conflict (Nixon 2011). It also begs the question as to why Taliban fighters should be brought to justice if their mujahideen counter-parts were able to get away with the crimes they committed, including those against the very Taliban they are now trying to reintegrate. Indeed, the programme itself does not speak of justice, but only of grievance resolution. With national processes in question and impunity continuing to prevail, the calls to tackle transitional justice and reconciliation from the bottom-up, with communities settling their grievances first and engaging government at a later stage until “we can move up to national discussions”, are growing (Theros/Kaldor 2011: 31; The Liaison Office 2011a). Pressured by civil society and international lobbying, the APRP has now recognized the need to “[m] obilize civil society organizations to facilitate customary justice providers to support restorative justice as a mechanism to reconcile insurgents into communities” (Afghanistan Peace And Reintegration Program 2011: 9). That being said, the same document (APRP) also highlighted the need to fine-tune the terms of interaction between the government and customary justice systems and develop a more specific action plan. Drawing extensively on the previous work of The Liaison Office, this paper suggests the use of restorative customary mechanisms, focussing on restorative justice as a way to initiate such a grassroots process of transitional justice, even if these bodies, at first, only deal with relatively minor offenses and are unable to address more massive human rights violations and war crimes (e.g., a larger number of killings). It is worth emphasizing that reconciliation in many ways “harmonizes with Afghan traditions that stress pragmatic bargaining and flexible alliances” (Suhrke et al. 2009: 12).  Susanne Schmeidl 3. The need for some form of transitional justice and accountability As noted, there is a tendency by the Afghan government, and its interna- tional supporters, to focus reintegration programmes mostly on disarming fighters, compensating them for their ‘loss’ of weapons and trying to inte- grate them through development programmes. The notion of accounta- bility for crimes committed is either intentionally or unintentionally over- looked. Assuming that a majority join the Taliban because of a lack of jobs or out of poverty is, however, fundamentally flawed. The new Taliban insurgency is more diverse than the first movement in the 1990s (Schmeidl/ Miszak 2011). “Afghans clearly differentiate between Taliban with a political or ideological objective, often accused of being externally steered and funded, and mid- and low-level commanders and foot soldiers who join and support the Taliban for other reasons” (The Liaison Office 2010a: 3). There are, for example, ‘political opportunists’, such as former muja- hideen commanders or local strongmen that hope to gain political clout through joining the insurgency, and/or attempt to gain advantages in local resource conflicts. Communities may need the political backing of government officials in order to deal with strongmen, as some may very well be ‘spoilers of peace’ that benefit from the status quo on which their supremacy rests and are thus unlikely to willingly address the grievances that are driving some of the insurgency. Then there are ‘economic opportunists’ and criminal elements (e.g., drug and weapons dealers) that find it opportune to hide within the Taliban. Some of these elements cannot be reintegrated without addressing their past actions; otherwise they might disturb the peace in communi- ties in the future. In particular, criminal elements (Taliban-e duzd or thief Taliban; van Bijlert 2009: 160) need to be punished in some form, as more often than not the Taliban itself cleanses its ranks of these individuals once they have gained control in an area. Especially problematic are those Taliban that have political (because they were sidelined from political processes and government positions) or justice grievances, especially if they suffered past injustice at the hands of government officials or strongmen linked to the government. Communities The Quest for Transitional Justice in Afghanistan will be hard-pressed to address their grievances without the support of the Afghan government. Reintegration might be impossible, without some form or admittance and apology, if the local process is led by the very government officials that have committed rights violations. Here, a lengthier process of dealing with the past (especially injustices) is necessary. In light of the above, “[r]eintegration needs to be understood as a process rather than a one-time event”, which involves an understanding of the grievances that have led an individual (or community) to join the insurgency and the conditions that are needed to bring them back to peace (The Liaison Office 2011a: 2). It is here that customary justice may be of assistance. 4. Customary mechanisms and transitional justice Customary law (rawaj) in Afghanistan is a rather complex set of rules and regulations based on group norms and accepted community practices that are rarely codified and tend to differ between communities and over time (Wily 2003; Wardak 2004).3 It rests largely on the oral history of those using it (spin giri/rishsafed or white-bearded elders) in each community. Though customary justice seems a potent tool for reconciliation, due to its focus on restorative justice rather than retributive justice, its use for transitional justice has been largely left unexplored. While the Afghan government has acknowledged the need to engage with customary structures (Islamic Republic of Afghanistan 2008), and elders have offered their services to the state, the pending ‘Draft Law on Dispute Resolution Shuras and Jirgas’ does little to utilize the strength of customary justice providers and more to control something the state feels threatened by. There are further concerns by both women and human rights advocates about the violation of women’s rights under customary laws and about the fact that customary justice lacks alignment with national and international law (Barfield et al. 2006). There is also the occasional critique – not so much in the international community as from some government officials – of customary justice’s lack of alignment with sharia (The Liaison Office 2011b). This section first outlines the elements of customary justice that are beneficial for transitional justice purposes, using the example of the Pash- tunwali of the Pashtun ethnic group (Glatzer 1998; Steul 1981), while also  Susanne Schmeidl highlighting the areas of traditional justice practice that need some refine- ment in order to meet the needs of a genuine reconciliation and transitional justice process. 4.1 The benefits of customary law and its institutions for transitional justice First, customary justice institutions have shown considerable persist- ence and accessibility. While formal state law collapsed during the Afghan wars, customary justice has shown remarkable resilience, even in the light of internal and external challenges from various actors, including the Taliban. Even today, after extensive international assistance has been poured into the formal justice system while relatively little attention and funding was paid to the informal system, the latter still handles the vast majority (an estimated 80 to 90 per cent) of all disputes in areas not controlled by the Taliban (Barfield et al. 2006; The Asia Foundation 2010; Wardak 2004). In Afghanistan’s rich and layered legal history, formal state law has always co-existed with religious (shari’a) and customary law (Barfield et al. 2006). As the Afghan State, and with it the formal court system, never fully reached beyond urban areas (and still does not), it, in many ways, has been irrelevant for the rural majority (Wardak 2004; Wimmer/Schetter 2002). Traditional customary institutions, in contrast, are not only consid- ered more accessible, but also more swift in dispensing justice (Schmeidl 2011). Many government officials (e.g., governors and chiefs of police), including the independent department of Huqooq (rights) of the Ministry of Justice, which is tasked with helping to resolve civil disputes outside the courts, frequently refer disputants to customary resolution mechanisms, with the reference to the shari’a principle of sulh (peace; Barfield et al. 2006: 19; The Liaison Office 2009a, 2011b). An annual survey by The Asia Foundation (2010), supporting more qualitative findings by other sources (The Liaison Office 2009a, 2009b), concluded: “More than four-fifths (86) of respondents agree that the local customary mechanisms of jirga/shura [see Box 1] are accessible. Around three quarters agree that local jirgas/shuras are fair and trusted (73) and more than two-thirds agree that they follow local norms and values (70), are effective at delivering justice (69) and resolve cases promptly (66)” The Quest for Transitional Justice in Afghanistan (The Asia Foundation 2010: 132). Disruptions caused by the Afghan wars have started to reduce the number of jirgas, with more and more disputes being settled by shuras or individual tribal or religious figures. Customary justice bodies A jirga is an ad hoc and temporary decision-making mechanism4 chiefly focussing on resolving communal disputes. The form and composition of a jirga depends on the dispute dealt with, but by and large includes tribal elders, community notables and sometimes religious figures and, since the Afghan wars, also commanders (Jones-Pauly/ Nojumi 2004). Once a jirga decision or ruling (prikra) is reached, it is binding for the entire community and the jirga is dissolved (Wardak 2004: 326). Before the proceedings begin, all parties involved must agree on which version of tribal laws (narkh) will be used in the mediation or resolution process. This may even include elements of sharia, which is increasingly invoked in the south. A shura is a more permanent local council that was introduced during the Afghan wars as a way for commanders to influence community deci- sions (Barfield et al. 2006). Today, shuras have become semi-formal, as the government has created district and provincial shuras under various programmes, such as the Afghan Social Outreach Programme (ASOP) of the Independent Directorate for Local Governance (IDLG). There are also ulema shuras, councils of religious scholars, which are linked to the Ministry of Hajj and Religious Affairs. More recently, non-govern- mental organizations, such as The Liaison Office, and USAID contrac- tors (USAID 2011) have also set up shuras working on alternative conflict resolution using customary law elements integrated with sharia and stat- utory law, the latter promoted through training. Shuras also mediate disputes (mostly property, family and business but also a sizeable criminal caseload), similarly disputing parties can also approach individual elders (spin giri) or religious figures to help them settle a dispute.  Susanne Schmeidl Secondly, customary law focuses on restorative and not retributive justice. As with any community rights approach the emphasis is less on punishing individuals than restoring harmony and peace in communities (Barfield et al. 2006). Retributive justice here is secondary, as most customary justice providers lack the enforcement elements of formal justice (e.g., police and jails). Instead, the mechanisms and rulings emphasize the accountability of the offender while also giving him a way back into the community (Mona- ghan 2008). While nobody goes to jail, however, there is still ‘punishment’. Wrongdoers are ‘sentenced’ for crimes committed and have to ask for forgiveness from the family of the victim (Wardak 2004 provides a detailed description of the process of asking for and granting forgiveness, which involves multiple family and community members, both men and women). In addition, customary law stipulates clear compensation (or blood money) to be paid for crimes committed and occasionally also the death penalty for severe crimes (Rzehak 2011; International Legal Foundation 2004). However, how and what form of compensation is paid will likely need some more improvement in order to comply to International Human Rights Laws. A much-criticized practise under Pashtunwali for example, is the exchange of women (baad ) as a form of compensation, which violates individual rights. This is often practised, however, in the absence of other valuables, as non-compensation can lead to a blood feud between communities, hence provoking conflict escalation and (further) bloodshed.5 With increasing prosperity in communities, however, elders are using this practice less today than in the past (USAID 2011). 4.2 Limitations of customary justice mechanisms for transitional justice Despite some clear benefits, customary mechanisms should not be engaged uncritically. Their limitations vis-à-vis reconciliation need to be clearly understood and addressed, in order to ensure that they do not fail due to being overburdened. The effectiveness of the informal system rests on community cohesion and the sharing of common values and attitudes, which tend to disinte- grate when communities are fragmented, as has happened throughout the years of the Afghan wars and also under the current Karzai administra- tion. There is evidence that strong individuals can and will “subvert the The Quest for Transitional Justice in Afghanistan principles of equity upon which the [customary justice] system relies for its popular legitimacy” (Barfield et al. 2006: 3), with jirga mediators no longer functioning independently, but rather as puppets of strongmen, for either patronage or financial interests (The Liaison Office 2008). Thus, bringing to justice strongmen, whether former mujahideen or Taliban commanders, may be difficult without the backing of the Afghan State and its interna- tional supporters. As a result, a customary system may be more effective in dealing with reintegrating foot soldiers than higher level individuals. Secondly, as each tribe has its own version of Pashtunwali, communi- ty-based customary mechanisms are already hard pressed for addressing inter-tribal, little alone inter-ethnic or inter-sectarian grievances, as well as crimes committed far away from the community where an ex-com- batant comes from, and so wishes to reintegrate into (Barfield et al. 2006). While possible in principle, the need for a greater jirga would be given, with elders from both communities who are well versed in the specific narkh of their tribe in attendance. As the Taliban is aware of the limi- tations of ‘customary jurisdiction,’ they often send fighters from one community further away for battle, with ‘local’ Taliban taking over once an area has been taken control of. Thus, customary justice may only be able to deal with such local Taliban, who may also have only committed lesser crimes. Thirdly, while the customary system may be considered, on the whole, as being less corrupt than the formal system, corruption and bribery have also made inroads into the jirga system (even if they are less prevalent than among state judges). While in the past tribal notables saw resolving conflicts as a community service, in recent years tijaraati elders (commercial elders) have set up shop in district centres rendering their services purely for financial benefit (The Liaison Office 2009a). Furthermore, in a society where hospi- tality is particularly valued and seen as a sign of grandeur, it seems impor- tant that a local customary mechanism tasked with reconciliation involves offering food to those in attendance, as such gestures of generosity can create trust, even among the most difficult and hardened conflict parties, and hence set the stage for an amicable solution (The Liaison Office 2009b: 12-13). Thus, there would be a need to provide support for customary mechanisms to offer their services free of charge. This is only possible through some form of external or government funding, as can be provided via the APRP.  Susanne Schmeidl Lastly, and possibly most importantly, customary mechanisms in general, and Pashtunwali in particular, have also been much criticized for their exclusion of women. In theory, all Pashtun (men) have an equal status (especially in front of the law) and no one should possess more rights and power than others (Schmeidl/Karokhail 2009). This equality, however, is often limited to male elites of a certain age and standing and, by extension, is inapplicable to all women and younger males (Barfield et al. 2006). In addition to the law itself being applied unevenly, customary bodies (shura or jirgas) traditionally included neither women nor young men. 4.3 The way forward: the devil always lies in the details The above discussion shows that customary justice has some impor- tant reconciliatory elements, yet also holds clear limitations. For example, while customary institutions can address, and already have successfully addressed, community disputes, such as resource conflicts (The Asia Foundation 2010), they are limited to dealing with rights violations by strongmen and former government officials. This may limit reconciliatory processes to foot soldiers and low-level commanders at first and, addition- ally, to those ex-combatants who don’t see rights violations by government officials as their main grievances. While here customary mechanisms can clearly build a bridge between insurgent fighters and the Afghan Govern- ment, the latter needs to be willing to address ‘spoilers’ within their ranks and possibly to hand out compensation on their behalf. In addition, the Afghan Government needs to realize the indepen- dence of customary justice providers when dealing with reconciliation. Only then can they seen to be neutral when addressing grievances, rather than working on behalf of an already discredited government. This, however, is not to say that oversight should not exist. Thus, The Liaison Office has been exploring the establishment of an ‘Association for Customary Justice Providers’ (The Liaison Office 2011a) which could work on setting clear standards, both as to who is best skilled as well as to who can engineer solutions and ways of recon- ciliation that most community members will perceive as just, while also setting standards for jirga procedures more generally. Such an association, if independent, can then decide on whom to include (rather than relying on government appointees) and begin recording decisions made, which The Quest for Transitional Justice in Afghanistan would help to improve transparency. Rather than individual customary justice providers being controlled by the Afghan State, the association can help to supervise conflict resolution provided by its (accredited) members, much along the lines of a professional association (e.g. of mediators and arbitrators) ensuring the quality of service delivery. For this purpose TLO has also proposed the creation of ‘ jirga houses’ where this association could not only hold its meetings, store its records and reference documents, as well as undertaking additional capacity- building activities such as training courses on Afghan statutory and sharia law, but also on how to best work towards transitional justice. If such an association were to be initially supported by donors, the problem of payments and corruption would be irrelevant. The associa- tion, however, could also work on setting fee structures with the long- term aim of being self-funding; and it might also explore the possibility of establishing a legal aid fund for those unable to afford the services of association elders. While initially such an association can work to support village justice providers, it can also move to join district and provincial justice bodies, with the ultimate aim of being able to deal with inter-community prob- lems. There is also a possibility of linking up with different regional asso- ciations to jointly work on inter-ethnic and inter-sectarian reconciliation, albeit this being more a long-term goal as it would necessitate strong local associations in the first instance, and efforts of trust building between the different groups of justice providers. The Liaison Office tried such a first dialogue in March 2011 (The Liaison Office 2011c), which indicated a will- ingness to exchange experiences and expertise. The gender bias of customary justice providers may also not be as insurmountable as some may think. While women’s groups in particular criticize customary justice for this all-male ethos, some do see it also as a form of conflict resolution where women can be involved (The Liaison Office 2011d). In most cases the process of asking forgiveness involves not only individuals, but entire families, hence also women. Furthermore, participants at a recent workshop of The Liaison Office identified numerous historical mediation roles that women have played – both in Pashtun and non-Pashtun communities – that could be employed to bolster local reconciliation and grievance resolution efforts (The Liaison Office 2011d).  Susanne Schmeidl All of this could be built upon to give women a larger role, not just in the process of forgiveness, but also, for example, in deciding how much compensation needs to be paid in order to reintegrate an offender back into the community without violating the rights of women. There are already cases in Afghanistan’s Southeast of women sitting on shuras alongside men. Furthermore, many Community Development Councils of the National Solidarity Program (NSP) include women. These have been increasingly approached for conflict resolution, even though their main mandate is development. Under APRP, NSP is the recipient of some 50 Million US Dollars for the purpose of assisting communities with reintegrating ex-combatants. Here, following a correct sequence is of great importance. “Outside assistance should come only after communities have resolved underlying conflicts and grievances that facilitated insurgency recruitment, as opposed to the current practice which is to give aid first and hope that this will prompt stability” (The Liaison Office 2011a: 5). Furthermore, the association of customary justice providers can also be encouraged to include women mediators. Some elders have already expressed considerable enthusiasm for the idea, and have shown a willing- ness to pilot women’s subcommittees in local associations that could be consulted and brought into negotiations in order to ensure that women’s rights are not violated. First pilots of this will start in some provinces of Afghanistan’s Southeast where The Liaison Office has worked longest with elders, both on the setting of standards and the opening up of public spaces for women. The idea is to start small and then have elders share their experience of working with women with other elders in order to encourage them to include women in their associations elsewhere. The sharing of such concrete experiences of men who have worked successfully with women is often more powerful in bringing women into previously all-male bodies than top-down quotas, even though this is often lobbied for by women’s groups. When working with customary justice providers it is thus crucial to identify male allies in the attempt to promote the advancement of women. Traditional justice institutions have also made headway vis-à-vis the reduction of discriminatory practises such as baad. Exchanging women was largely intended as a way to provide valuable but non-monetary compensation. However, as communities have grown more prosperous, The Quest for Transitional Justice in Afghanistan they have access to other resources (e.g., property, valuables such as cars) that can be used to pay compensation. Furthermore, some communities have questioned the long-term durability of a settlement where women have been exchanged, especially given that the exchanged girls are often not treated well and sometimes even commit suicide. As a result, rather than lessening conflict, baad can actually lead to a renewed dispute. These concerns have led elders to abolish this practise in some parts of Afghanistan (Afghanistan Today 2011; USAID 2011). It is here again, that the association can help by working on a standard setting that disallows practices that violate women’s rights. Contrary to popular belief, elders do have the right to break new ground in customary law as long as this is met with general agreement by other customary justice providers and the communities they represent (Schmeidl 2011). Those elders consulted about the association have already noted the wish to align their practises with sharia and statutory law, especially the Afghan constitution. Hence, the seeds are sown for a change within which will very likely be more sustainable than imposing rules and regulations from above. 5. Conclusion This article has explored the advancement of reconciliation and transi- tional justice in Afghanistan through the utilisation of customary justice. Up to now, the issue of transitional justice and dealing with the past has been a taboo in Afghanistan, with the Afghan government preferring providing amnesty to past mujahideen fighters and warlords. Nevertheless, the argument of peace first and justice second has not helped the peace process ushered in by the 2001 Bonn Agreement. Instead, insecurity has been on the rise and the Taliban insurgency has partially reemerged as a result of poor governance and unaddressed grie vances. Espe- cially in the area of justice provision, the Taliban, with its sharia courts, has been clearly ‘out-governing’ the current Karzai admi nistration. While it may indeed be true that it is difficult to combat impunity at a national level, especially as long as past ‘offenders’ are part of govern- ment bodies (up to and including ministries, Parliament, and the High Peace Council), this should not preclude working at the grassroots level  Susanne Schmeidl with customary mechanisms that have survived the past years of war and political upheaval. In particular, their focus on restorative rather than retributive justice and community harmonization shows that such mechanisms can play a valuable role in furthering transitional justice at a community level. Taking the above limitations of customary justice into account, as well as the troubled history of state-civil society relations in Afghanistan (Schmeidl 2007, 2009), this article has discussed the possibility of devel- oping a process that can provide communities with the space to reinte- grate insurgent fighters, especially those that have committed crimes and/ or damaged ties to their families and community. For this, however, the limitations of customary justice providers – such as their representativeness, reach and qualifications – need to be understood and overcome. Here, the article has introduced the idea of a best practice association, which The Liaison Office is currently setting up in some parts of Afghanistan. Such an association can not only function as a tool for setting standards, but can also break new ground on aligning customary justice more with sharia and Afghan state law, including the constitution. As noted, such an asso- ciation can also work toward including women, and ensuring their rights are not violated. With the strength of customary justice institutions in rural and hard to reach areas, international actors are encouraged to overcome their reser- vations about customary justice and embrace a process that could bring peace to communities. Here, however, donor support to the Afghan Peace and Reintegration Program should be used wisely and funds (or projects) only provided to communities that have started to address reconciliation and justice issues first. Otherwise, the cycle of violence will be hard to break in Afghanistan. 1 I would like to thank my colleagues Nick Miszak and Peyton Cooke for useful input into this article. 2 The ‘“big tent” approach to government’ largely focused on the inclusion of strongmen, trying to bring them into government (rather than fighting them). Inadvertently though many in the end held far more power than a fledgling state could potentially manage, managing to spoil from within. The Quest for Transitional Justice in Afghanistan 3 It has been influenced by the turmoil of the Afghan wars and resulting displace- ments. Within the Pashtunwali, the customary law of the Pashtuns, for example, each tribe has their specific narkh (set of customary rules, comparable to a civil code), which only their own elders are allowed to interpret. 4 Jirga originates from jirg, ‘which means a wrestling ring’, or ‘circle’, but is com- monly used to refer to a gathering of people. There is a similar word in Turkish, which makes some scholars believe it originates from there (Wardak 2004: 326). 5 The alternative would be a blood feud that can easily escalate into a full-blown tribal conflict. Since other ethnic groups in Afghanistan do not use baad and it is in violation of the religious sharia law, Pashtuns have been under some pressure to abandon it (including by the Taliban), so it is an outcome that is justified on a cost-benefit basis. References Afghanistan Peace and Reintegration Program (2011): Conclusion Paper of APRP Review Conference. Kabul: Afghanistan Peace and Reintegration Program. Afghanistan Today (2011): The end of a tradition: Tribal elders in Khost have banned the use of girls as reparation for crimes and limited the bride-price. http://www.afghanistan-today.org/article/?id=105&lang=en, 15.5.2011. AIHRC (2005): A Call for Justice. Kabul: Afghan Independent Human Rights Commission. http://www.aihrc.org.af/Rep_29_Eng/rep29_1_05 call4justice. pdf, 10.5.2011. Barfield, Thomas/Nojumi, Neamat/Thier, J. Alexander (2006): The Clash of Two Goods: State and Non-State Dispute Resolution in Afghanistan. Washington, DC: United States Institute of Peace. ww.usip.org/ruleoflaw/projects/clash_ two_goods.pdf, 23.9.2008. Frogh, Wazhma (2010a): PEACE JIRGA BLOG 10: The Afghan Peace Jirga, where peace means politics. In: Afghanistan Analyst Network Blog, 4.6.2010. http:// www.aan-afghanistan.org/index.asp?id=802, 5.6.2010. Frogh, Wazhma (2010b): Will the Afghan government’s reintegration and reconcili- ation efforts bring peace to Afghanistan? In: Afghan Voices Series. Sydney: The Lowy Institute. Glatzer, Berndt (1998): Is Afghanistan on the brink of ethnic and tribal disintegra- tion? In: Maley, William (ed.): Fundamentalism Reborn? Afghanistan and the Taliban. Lahore: Vanguard Books, 167-182. Human Rights Watch (2010): Afghanistan: Repeal Amnesty Law. New York: Human Rights Watch News, 10.3.2010. http://www.hrw.org/en/ news/2010/03/10/afghanistan-repeal-amnesty-law. 1.4.2011. International Legal Foundation (2004): The Customary Laws of Afghanistan. Kabul: ILF Report.  Susanne Schmeidl Islamic Republic of Afghanistan (2008): Draft summary of ANDS Justice Sector Strategy. Kabul: Afghanistan National Development Strategy (ANDS). www. ands.gov.af/ands/jcmb/site/src/Meeting20and20Documents/seventh20 JCMB/files/IV.20ANDS20Documents/Justic20Sector20Strategy,20 Draft20Summary20-20English.pdf, 9.2.2009. Islamic Republic of Afghanistan (2010): Afghanistan Peace and Reintegration Program (APRP), Draft. Kabul: National Security Council, D&R-Commis- sion. Jones-Pauly, Catherine/Nojumi, Neamat (2004): Balancing relations between society and state: Legal steps towards national reconciliation and reconstruc- tion of Afghanistan. In: American Journal of Comparative Law 52 (4), 825-857. Mojumdar, Aunohita (2010): Afghans talk, Taliban shoot. Asia Times Online, 2.6.2010. http://www.atimes.com/atimes/South_Asia/LF03Df01.html, 5.5.2011. Monaghan, Rachel (2008): Community-based justice in Northern Ireland and South Africa. In: International Criminal Justice Review 18 (1), 83-105. Nixon, Hamish (2011): Achieving Durable Peace: Afghan Perspectives on a Peace Process. Oslo/Bergen/Washington, DC: Peace Research Institute Oslo (PRIO)/ Michelsen Institute and United Institute of Peace. Rzehak, Lutz (2011): Doing Pashto: Pashtunwali as the ideal of honourable behav- iour and tribal life among the Pashtuns. Kabul: Afghanistan Analysts Network. Schmeidl, Susanne (2007): Civil Society and State-Building in Afghanistan. In: Danspeckgruber, Wolfgang F./Finn, Robert (eds.): Building State and Security in Afghanistan. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 102-127. Schmeidl, Susanne (2009): Promoting Civil Society in Afghanistan – Decon- structing Some Myths. In: Danspeckgruber, Wolfgang (ed.): Petersberg Papers on Afghanistan and the Region. Princeton: Lichtenstein Institute on Self-De- termination, 68-74. Schmeidl, Susanne (2011): Engaging traditional justice mechanisms in Afghanistan: State-building opportunity or dangerous liaison? In: Mason, Whit (ed.): The Rule of Law in Afghanistan: Casualties of Myopia. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Schmeidl, Susanne/Karokhail, Masood (2009): The role of non-state actors in ‘community-based policing’ – an exploration of the arbakai (tribal police) in south-eastern Afghanistan. In: Contemporary Security Policy 30 (2), 318-342. Schmeidl, Susanne/Miszak, Nick (2011): For a Fistful of Dollars: The Selling out of Reconciliation and Reintegration in Afghanistan. In: Danspeckgruber, Wolf- gang (ed.): Working Toward Peace and Prosperity in Afghanistan. Liechten- stein Colloquium Report 5. Princeton: Lynne Rienner Publishers. Steul, Willy (1981): Pashtunwali: Ein Ehrenkodex und seine rechtliche Relevanz. Wiesbaden: Franz Steiner. Suhrke, Astri/Wimpelmann Chaudhary, Torunn/Hakimi, Aziz/Harpviken, Kris- tian Berg/ Sarwari, Akbar/Strand, Arne (2009): The Quest for Transitional Justice in Afghanistan Conciliatory approaches to the insurgency in Afghanistan: An overview. Bergen: Chr. Michelsen Institute (CMI Report R 2009: 1). The Asia Foundation (2010): Afghanistan in 2010. A Survey of the Afghan People. Kabul: The Asia Foundation. The Liaison Office (2008): Land Based Conflict In Afghanistan: The Case of Paktia. Kabul: The Liaison Office. The Liaison Office (2009a): Linkages between state and non-state justice systems in Eastern Afghanistan: Evidence from Jalalabad, Nangarhar and Ahmad Aba, Paktia. Kabul: The Liaison Office. The Liaison Office (2009b): An evaluation of the Khost Commission on Conflict Mediation (CCM). Kabul: The Liaison Office. The Liaison Office (2010a): Reintegrating the Insurgency Piece by Peace in Uruzgan Province: Aspects of a comprehensive peace building strategy. TLO Policy Brief 2/2010. Kabul: The Liaison Office. The Liaison Office (2010b): Reconciliation and Reintegration in Loya Paktia: Local Perspectives and Recommendations. TLO Policy Brief 3/2010. Kabul: The Liaison Office. The Liaison Office (2011a): How Civil Society can assist and enhance the APRP. Presentation at the APRP Review Conference, Kabul, Afghanistan 10-11 May 2011. Kabul: The Liaison Office. The Liaison Office (2011b), Formal and Informal Justice in Paktia and Nangarhar: A TLO Working Paper. Kabul/Washington, DC: The Liaison Office/The United States Institute of Peace. The Liaison Office (2011c): Empowering Traditional Justice – Creating a Best Prac- tices Association. Workshop report. Kabul: The Liaison Office. The Liaison Office (2011d): Moving Beyond Tokenism: The Role of Women in Peace and Reintegration in Afghanistan. Workshop report. Kabul: The Liaison Office. Theros, Marika/Kaldor, Mary (2011), Building Afghan Peace from the Ground Up. New York: The Century Foundation, Project on Afghanistan in Its Regional and Multilateral Dimensions. USAID (2011): Afghanistan Rule of Law Stabilization Program (Informal Compo- nent) Assessment. Kabul/Washington, DC: United States Agency for Interna- tional Development. van Bijlert, Martine (2009): Unruly Commanders and Violent Power Struggles: Taliban Networks in Uruzgan. In: Giustozzi, Antonio (ed.): Decoding the New Taliban: Insights from the Afghan Field. London/New York: Hurst & Company/Columbia University Press, 155-179. Waldman, Matt (2010): Golden Surrender? The Risks, Challenges, and Implications of Reintegration in Afghanistan. Kabul: Afghanistan Analysts Network. Wardak, Ali (2004): Building a post-war justice system in Afghanistan. In: Crime, Law & Social Change 41, 319-341.  Susanne Schmeidl Wilder, Andrew/Lister, Sarah (2007): State-building at the Subnational Level in Afghanistan: A Missed Opportunity. In: Danspeckgruber, Wolfgang/Finn, Robert (eds.): Building State and Security in Afghanistan. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 85-102. Wily, Liz Alden (2003): Land Rights in Crisis: Restoring Tenure Insecurity in Afghanistan. Kabul: Afghanistan Research and Evaluation Unit. Wimmer, Andreas/Schetter, Conrad (2002): Staatsbildung zuerst: Empfehlungen zum Wiederauf bau und zur Befriedung Afghanistans. Discussion Papers on Development Policy. Bonn: Zentrum für Entwicklungsforschung (ZEF). Winterbotham, Emily (2010): The State of Transitional Justice in Afghanistan. Policy Note Series. Kabul: Afghanistan Research and Evaluation Unit (AREU). Abstracts Based upon an analysis of the peace process in Afghanistan since 2011, the article argues that past top-down approaches have failed to achieve the twin goals of peace and justice. Thus, customary justice and its asso- ciated structures offers an alternative approach to furthering reconcilia- tion and addressing grievances, as well as to ensuring accountability for wrongs committed at the community level. Drawing from the work of The Liaison Office, the article highlights the advantages of customary justice institutions, but also cautions that their limitations (e.g., discrimination against women, an inability to reign in strongmen and address inter-ethnic conflicts) need to be addressed. The article concludes with the recommen- dation to establish a best practice association that can set standards for customary justice providers and guarantee the inclusion of women. Anhand einer Analyse des Friedensprozesses in Afghanistan seit 2011 zeigt dieser Artikel, dass Top-down-Ansätze in den letzten Jahren weder Frieden noch Gerechtigkeit geschaffen haben. Eine Alternative bietet das Gewohnheitsrecht (customary justice) und dessen Institutionen, um die Versöhnung weiter voranzutreiben und Ungerechtigkeiten, die auf Gemein- schaftsebene stattgefunden haben, aufzuarbeiten. Ausgehend von der Arbeit des „Liaison Office“ beleuchtet die Autorin die Vorteile von tradi- tionellen Rechtsverfahren, dabei müssen aber auch deren Einschränkungen The Quest for Transitional Justice in Afghanistan bedacht werden (zum Beispiel Benachteiligung von Frauen, eine Unfähig- keit Kriegsfürsten die Stirn zu bieten und inter-ethnische Konflikte zu bearbeiten). Der Artikel schließt mit dem Vorschlag, einen Zusammen- schluss von traditionellen Rechtsschlichtern zu gründen, der Standards für die Anwendung des Gewohnheitsrechts und die Einbeziehung der Frauen garantieren kann. Susanne Schmeidl 137 Boundary Street Clovelly, NSW 2031 Australia susanne@schmeidl.com work_3eupra2zgjh7bhz6m6hwu4bvwe ---- Correction to: Global Justice Index Report Vol.:(0123456789) Chinese Political Science Review https://doi.org/10.1007/s41111-020-00154-1 1 3 CO R R E C T I O N Correction to: Global Justice Index Report Yanfeng Gu1 · Xuan Qin1 · Zhongyuan Wang1 · Chunman Zhang1 · Sujian Guo1 © The Author(s) 2020 Correction to: Chinese Political Science Review https ://doi.org/10.1007/s4111 1-020-00148 -z The article “Global Justice Index Report”, written by Yanfeng Gu · Xuan Qin · Zhongyuan Wang · Chunman Zhang and Sujian Guo, was originally published elec- tronically on the publisher’s internet portal on 4th June 2020 without open access. With the author(s)’ decision to opt for Open Choice the copyright of the article changed on 27th July 2020 to © The Author(s) 2020 and the article is forthwith distributed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (https:// creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appro- priate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The original article has been corrected. The original article can be found online at https ://doi.org/10.1007/s4111 1-020-00148 -z. * Sujian Guo sguo@fudan.edu.cn 1 Fudan Institute for Advanced Study in Social Sciences, Fudan University, Shanghai, China http://orcid.org/0000-0002-2846-0303 https://doi.org/10.1007/s41111-020-00148-z http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1007/s41111-020-00154-1&domain=pdf https://doi.org/10.1007/s41111-020-00148-z Correction to: Global Justice Index Report Correction to: Chinese Political Science Review https​:doi.org10.1007s4111​1-020-00148​-z work_3fsnqmsbsvgt7mlukeojkly5vu ---- Human Rights and Social Justice laws Article Human Rights and Social Justice Neil Hibbert Department of Political Studies, University of Saskatchewan, 9 Campus Dr, Saskatoon, SK S7N 5A5, Canada; neil.hibbert@usask.ca; Tel.: +1-(306)-966-8944 Academic Editor: Bernadette Rainey Received: 1 September 2016; Accepted: 13 June 2017; Published: 16 June 2017 Abstract: This paper addresses the question of the normative domains of human rights and social justice. Today, the dominant view in political philosophy is that they occupy largely distinct spheres, with social justice being a set of stronger egalitarian norms and human rights functioning as baseline protections against common threats posed by states to the general interests of persons subjected to them. Reflecting on current human rights practice and discourse, this paper develops a reconstructed normative model of social justice and human rights as nested membership norms in political societies. By connecting membership to processes of political legitimacy, human rights are conceptualized as increasingly functioning as the language of contesting and reforming barriers of exclusion to that status. This leads to an understanding of the possible content of human rights that is dynamic and relational, bringing it closer in line with the egalitarianism of social justice. Keywords: human rights; social justice; political legitimacy; membership 1. Introduction Domestic and international human rights documents and discourses are characterized by conceptual and normative links between the aims of human rights and social justice. As James Griffin observes, disapprovingly, the foundational document of the modern human rights movement, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR), is characterized by a “whole scale inclusion of justice among human rights . . . (and) includes not only procedural justice, but also distributive justice and fairness” (Griffin 2008, p. 186). The UDHR’s preamble indeed states that human rights are the ‘foundation’ of justice ‘in the world’, and many of its articles include egalitarian aspirations across the full institutional range of modern political societies (UN General Assembly 1948). For example, in addition to articles covering procedural justice (e.g., article 10), UDHR article 7 establishes the human right to equal public protection against discrimination; article 21.2 states the right to ‘equal access to public service’; article 21.3 includes broad entitlements to democratic rights; article 23.2 contains the right to ‘equal pay for equal work’, with 23.3 adding the ‘right to just and favourable remuneration’; and, article 26 develops a range of educational and opportunity rights. The UDHR’s invocation of these aims is widely re-iterated in subsequent international and domestic human rights documents (e.g., the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, and the Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities) as well as by a diverse range of actors in human rights advocacy groups and networks (Clapham 2007, pp. 160–62; Garcea and Hibbert 2011, pp. 53–56; Hucker 1997; Jetsckhe 1999, pp. 144–46). In quite a strong contrast, what can be considered the dominant philosophical view in contemporary liberal political philosophy is that human rights and social justice occupy largely distinct normative domains (Beitz 2009; Cohen 2010; Jones 2010; Nickel 2007; Rawls 1999b; Raz 2010; Risse 2012). On the dominant philosophical view, while overlapping in cases of constitutionally essential equal civil and political rights, social justice is theorized as requiring significantly greater distributive equality across a range of political and socioeconomic institutions than human rights. Laws 2017, 6, 7; doi:10.3390/laws6020007 www.mdpi.com/journal/laws http://www.mdpi.com/journal/laws http://www.mdpi.com http://dx.doi.org/10.3390/laws6020007 http://www.mdpi.com/journal/laws Laws 2017, 6, 7 2 of 16 The dominant view can therefore be understood as presenting a ‘discontinuous’ conception of the normative relationship between social justice and human rights. As Charles Jones frames it, while different conceptions of human rights will vary as to the “extent of justice commitments” they cover, the requirements of social justice include “further specifications on the range of legitimate inequality of basic goods (that) are compatible with universal rights protections” (Jones 2010, p. 133). The dominant philosophical view thus presents a type of human rights-plus conception of social justice: social justice includes human rights but contains a further conception of equality rights that are not human rights. The aim of this paper is to push back against the dominant, discontinuous, view of the relationship between the normative domains of human rights and social justice, and to outline a normative model of human rights that overlaps more fully with an egalitarian conception of social justice. This reformed normative model of human rights is ‘political’ in the sense of being based on a reflection on current human rights practice, understood to consist of both institutional and discursive elements (Beitz 2009, p. 8). The purpose of a normative model is to provide a ‘reconstructive account’ of the “norms and ideals that are implicit and play a structuring role in our practices” (Heath 2011, p. 28). Reflecting on current global and domestic human rights institutions and discourses suggests an ‘emergent’ and contested practice, marked by disagreement over the basic norms and values that ground the practice (Beitz 2009, pp. 8–9). Nevertheless, there is reason to hold that the normative dimensions of the development of human rights practice reflects a growing convergence on the dominant, egalitarian, philosophical understanding of the normativity of social justice. To account for this convergence, the goal of this paper is to outline an account of how social justice and human rights increasingly share normative space based on their grounding in the ideal of ‘membership’ in a political society, and both function at different levels of abstraction from political practice to protect against exclusions from that status. The discussion proceeds as follows: the first section presents a synthesized version of the dominant discontinuous philosophical view, which grounds human rights and social justice on distinct justificatory interests—the interest in common protections against standard associative threats and the interest in fair terms of inclusion in a relational status of political membership respectively. The next section presents the idea that reflection on the current human rights practice suggests that membership interests are a more appropriate justificatory grounds for capturing existing and deepening egalitarian elements of human rights, bringing them closer to the normativity of social justice. The third and fourth sections develop the idea of human rights and social justice as nested membership norms by exploring their respective roles in establishing and satisfying the conditions of political legitimacy. The final section defends this view against the objection that the distinctive aspect of human rights as international concern marks them off from many of the demands of social justice that are not coherently matters of international concern. 2. The Dominant Philosophical View of Human Rights and Social Justice Today, social justice in political philosophy is characterized as a strongly egalitarian norm. In Ronald Dworkin’s view, all plausible political philosophy is now, in an abstract moral way, egalitarian, such that theories of social justice rest on, and are evaluated by their correspondence to, the fundamental moral idea that people are equals, and as members of a political society are entitled to equal respect and consideration in the “design and administration of the political institutions that govern them” (Dworkin 1978, p. 189); see also Kymlicka on the idea that contemporary political philosophy has reached an ‘egalitarian plateau’ (Kymlicka 2002, p. 4). This, in turn, grounds significant requirements of distributive equality in egalitarian theories of social justice, such as, for example, John Rawls’ requirement of equal distributions of primary goods. In contrast, human rights, on the dominant view, while also resting on an abstract principle of equality, when worked out institutionally, are thought to be consistent with greater levels of inequality than social justice in the distribution of benefits and burdens in a political society. Instead of requiring interpersonal comparisons of relative Laws 2017, 6, 7 3 of 16 standing between members, human rights are theorized as establishing non-comparative baselines of entitlements and protections. This distinction between the normative domains of social justice and human rights differs somewhat from another prominent grounds for the discontinuous view. Often, social justice is distinguished from human rights along the lines of the distinction between political and civil rights, on the one hand, and socioeconomic rights on the other, whereby social justice includes the latter while human rights do not (O’Neill 2005). The understanding of the discontinuous view as presented in this paper, however, proceeds in a somewhat different direction. Under the dominant philosophical view, social justice and human rights both cover the full range of benefits and burdens that are involved in modern political societies, and so the distinction between civil/political and socioeconomic entitlements and exclusions is not the key dimension of the distinction. The discontinuity, rather, concerns the underpinning justifications, and their distributive requirements, of human rights and social justice across these areas of political practice. While covering the same areas of political and socioeconomic life, human rights, on the dominant philosophical view, require much less by way of an egalitarian distribution to be satisfied, than do standard theories of distributive justice. A prominent theoretical ground for the dominant, discontinuous view of human rights and social justice is a distinction between their underpinning justificatory interests, or what Charles Beitz calls their “justifying purposes” (Beitz 2009, pp. 128–29). Human rights and the further rights of social justice, he argues, “are grounded in interests of different degrees of urgency and therefore exert different weights” on the distributive requirements of political and socioeconomic institutions (Beitz 2009, p. 142). What types of justificatory interests, then, does the dominant philosophical view respectively rest human rights and social justice upon? One notable feature of the dominant philosophical view of human rights is that it treats human rights as distinctly political, which stands in contrast to a previous wave of theorizing in which human rights were treated as a euphemism for the older idea of natural rights (Cranston 1973; Finnis 2011). Natural rights are rights that are held by persons in all times and places, and concern basic interests of personhood that are stable across different political contexts. A political conception of human rights, in contrast, is context-dependent, and presumes specific interests that are only intelligible with reference to particular institutional practices (Buchanan 2005, pp. 73–74). While a theory of rights grounded in nothing but our humanity is undoubtedly an important element of theorizing rights, the problem of reducing a conception of human rights to such a conception is that it is, as Joseph Raz puts it, “so removed from the practice of human rights as to be irrelevant to it” (Raz 2010, p. 322). A principal evaluative component of a political conception of human rights is therefore that it captures important elements of current human rights practice in an institutional context that approximates current modes of political organization. On the dominant philosophical view, the most important element of the context of current human rights practice is the fact that states are the primary institutional arrangement for governing people; as Beitz puts it, the “practice of human rights as it has developed so far can only be understood as a revisionist appurtenance of a world of independent, territorial states” (Jones 2010, p. 128). Human rights are, on this conception, general norms for regulating the functioning of states as it concerns the general associative interests of those subjected to them. A further element of practice that limits the content of human rights, in the dominant view, is that, while standards for domestic states, human rights are also matters of international concern. This has the effect of universalizing the content of human rights across a diverse range of domestic societies organized by states by setting up shared standards for the international community for concern and action regarding a state’s treatment of its own members, and imposing common constraints on “the permissible exercise of the prerogatives traditionally associated with the norm of sovereignty” (Jones 2010, p. 133). The ‘justifying purpose’ in the dominant philosophical approach to human rights is, then, establishing common protections against standard and predictable associative threats created by states. These include a range of protections against the vulnerabilities created by exposure to the coercive capacities of states Laws 2017, 6, 7 4 of 16 and egregious forms of socioeconomic vulnerability the state can generate or neglect. The dominant view of human rights is sensitive to the current context of political practice, while maintaining the normative dimension of universality inherited from the natural rights tradition, by linking the content of human rights to the shared interests of persons subjected to states in common protections against standard and predictable associative threats. As mentioned, the standard view of social justice, in contrast, is grounded in the interest of equal respect and consideration of all interests relevant to living in a political society that fall under the purview of governing institutions, extending well beyond the interest in protections against general associative threats that grounds human rights. Treating persons with equal respect will involve making inter-personal comparisons between them to assess relative levels of advantage and disadvantage. This sort of justificatory interest can be understood as a membership interest, which is a deeper and more inclusive norm than that of common protections against predictable associative threats. As Joshua Cohen characterizes the idea of membership, “to be treated as a member is to have one’s interests given due consideration, both in the processes of authoritative decision-making, and in the content of those decisions” (Cohen 2010, p. 328). The idea of membership helps distinguish a voluntaristic associative system of legitimate cooperation from one of imposed domination, including a range of potential scenarios which may have sufficient protections against associative vulnerabilities to satisfy the dominant view of human rights. The ideal of membership, for example, is at the core of John Rawls’ distinction between domination as “merely socially coordinated activity . . . by orders issued by some central authority” and a genuinely legitimate system of social cooperation that is “guided by publicly recognized rules and procedures that those cooperating accept and regard as properly regulating their conduct” (Rawls 1993, p. 16). Because membership is inclusive, rather than a common baseline standard of treatment, it involves comparative assessments with the condition of other members and leads to egalitarian changes to barriers of exclusion. It permits variation in the demands of social justice across political societies based on different patterns of social exclusion that constitute membership interests in particular societies. A conception of social justice grounded on membership interests is therefore relational and dynamic in its content and institutional requirements. This stands in contrast to an absolute and universal conception of human rights that rests on the common justificatory interest in protections against standard associative threats. 3. Human Rights as Membership Norms Are common protections against standard associative threats the most appropriate justificatory interest on which to ground a political conception of human rights? There is reason to think not. Reflecting on current human rights practice reveals important egalitarian normative elements that suggest that interests related to inclusion in the status of membership, and the goal of legitimate social cooperation, better captures these dimensions. If so, this brings human rights much closer to the normative domain of social justice than under the dominant philosophical view. Of course the relevant point of evaluation for all theories of human rights is not necessarily providing an adequate “critical reconstruction of human rights as they are in the legal doctrine and practice of human rights” (Buchanan 2010, p. 680). This is, however, a crucial consideration in the case of political conceptions, to which the dominant philosophical view belongs, that presume existing institutional arrangements as the context of human rights, and aim to reconstruct a normative model of current human rights practice. Reflecting on current human rights practices to make salient their underlying normative logic reveals significant, and deepening, levels of egalitarianism that stretch beyond the conception of human rights as common protections against standard associative threats. These include, but are not limited to, formal equality before the law, participation rights, opportunity-oriented socioeconomic entitlements and anti-discrimination and employment equity rights (Rawls 1993; Garcea and Hibbert 2011; Hucker 1997). These kinds of human rights protections are comparative and relational, suggesting an inclusionary standard of membership, rather than a baseline standard of common protections. Laws 2017, 6, 7 5 of 16 If this is so, how might the egalitarian and relational elements of current human rights practice be normatively accounted for? One possibility is Allen Buchanan’s compelling egalitarian theory of human rights that departs from the non-egalitarian nature of the dominant model. Buchanan argues that there are seven distinct egalitarian elements of current human rights practice that are inconsistent with the standard protections against associative threats normative model (the ‘inclusive assumption’, ‘robust equality before the law’, ‘positive rights’, ‘equal political participation rights’, ‘anti-discrimination rights’, comparative assessments of an ‘adequate standard of living’ and the ‘right to work’) (Buchanan 2010, p. 683). On Buchanan’s view the institutional and discursive practice of human rights have evolved away from standard protections against predictable associative threats and towards an inclusive and relational idea of equality. He argues that the “most secure and straightforward grounding” for the egalitarian elements of human rights “is the idea of equal status” (Buchanan 2010, p. 687). Buchanan’s idea of status equality is conceptually similar to the justificatory idea of membership discussed above, given the central ideas of inclusion, comparative assessments of well-being and relative assessments of rights protection. The justificatory ground of equal status reflects the idea that human rights involve interests related to protections against exclusion from a social notion of status that is intelligible as being recognized and treated as a full member of a political society, rather than a subject. While developing in the direction of membership norms, Buchanan goes on to argue, however, that human rights remain normatively distinct from social justice because status equality, while extending beyond common protections against standard threats, does not presuppose “an egalitarian distributive principle,” as is the case with social justice. The status equality of human rights is distinct from the distributive equality required by egalitarian theories of social justice, and securing status equality through human rights is “compatible with a wide range of differences and with their social recognition in the form of material inequalities” (Buchanan 2010, p. 685). Equal status, on this conception, “constrains” material inequality without requiring the extent of distributive equality entailed by egalitarian theories of social justice. Buchanan holds that “a principle of equal distribution of resources or of well-being” ‘exceeds’ the protections needed for securing equal status through human rights (Buchanan 2010, p. 684). Buchanan therefore maintains the discontinuousness of the dominant philosophical view while incorporating egalitarian principles into his normative model of human rights based on the justificatory interest of status equality and its requirements of social inclusion and socially comparative assessments of ‘standards of living’. There is reason, however, to question the stability of this space between the status and distributive elements in an egalitarian concept of human rights. Equality of relational status entails fair terms of inclusion in both the material and socio-cultural life of a political association. As Will Kymlicka puts it, “one way to ensure that social relationships are egalitarian is to ensure that individuals have roughly equal shares of social resources” (Kymlicka 2002, p. 196). A similar connection between distributive and status equality is interestingly found in Rawls’ theory of justice. He argues that “perhaps the most important primary good is that of self-respect” (Rawls 1999a, p. 386). This entails elimination of barriers of exclusion to status equality, and is cashed out distributively as fair access to the “social bases of self-respect;” thus, a theory of justice that “gives more support to self-esteem than other principles is a strong reason . . . to adopt it” (Rawls 1999a, p. 386). Like in Kymlicka’s account, this links into robust distributive requirements of social justice because, according to Rawls, “our self-respect normally depends on the respect of others” and extending fair terms of inclusion to shared institutions is an expression of persons’ “respect for one another” (Rawls 1993, pp. 155–56). These at least plausible connections between status and distributive equality evoke Nancy Fraser ’s notion of a “false antithesis” between material inequalities and “recognitional” structures of “cultural domination . . . (and) social patterns of misrepresentation, interpretation and communication.” Much of social inequality, she argues, is “bivalent” and consists of complex intersections of “economic differentials and culturally constructed distinctions” (Fraser 1996, p. 7). While the notion of status is an abstract, recognitional, standing, it conditionally grounds concrete egalitarian distributive requirements. Indeed, if as Rawls Laws 2017, 6, 7 6 of 16 contends, the self-respect that comes from one’s status as a full member in a political community is “the most important primary good,” much of the materialist distributive requirements of social justice can be understood as grounded in that interest. The connections between status and distributive equality stabilize a conception of an overlapping normative domain of human rights and social justice as nested regulative principles for associative practices and institutions which function to protect against exclusions from status equality. The notion of nested principles here accounts for the fact that social justice and human rights function at different levels of abstraction from institutions. Social justice consists of structural principles that apply to the cumulative functioning of a political society over time as it affects the membership interests of those involved in it (Rawls 1999a, p. 6). Human rights, in contrast, function less deep in the structural background of a political society and apply more concretely in specific institutional settings. Take for example the idea of fair ‘equality of opportunity’ as a widely endorsed principle of social justice (Rawls 1999a, pp. 73–77). It is clearly linked to the idea of inclusion in the status of membership and is used to evaluate the way in which the institutions of a political society interactively function to shape persons’ prospects over time. A society is more or less just depending on how it structures the opportunities for political and socioeconomic participation held by its members. The principle of equality opportunity can be seen to ‘nest’ a host of subsequent human rights requirements as they pertain to the functioning of specific institutional settings as they feed back into the overall structure of opportunities, including: human rights in educational institutions (Ray and Tarrow 2014), societal and workplace discrimination oriented human rights (Gravel and Delpech 2008), human rights concerns regarding poverty alleviation (Vizard 2006), and ability and mobility oriented human rights. Human rights of these kinds work to address barriers of exclusion in particular institutional settings, while affecting the general condition of opportunity in a society. Generated human rights will be grounded in more concrete social identities and interests than the deeper, and necessarily more general, principles of social justice. By applying to more specified practices, they are also more easily, though not necessarily, translated into formal juridical and legislative entitlements. One notable example of this dynamic is the development in human rights protections of disabled persons as the primary mechanism of addressing unfair opportunity inequality based in disability. The development of human rights for disabled persons illustrates how the general concerns of social justice as regulative principles for a society’s major socioeconomic and political institutions ground more specified, though still rather abstract human rights conventions, which are subsequently incorporated at various levels of governance into legislative and legal reform. At the level of an egalitarian conception of social justice, mental and physical disabilities would be treated as unjust (i.e., morally arbitrary) barriers of exclusion—or denial of equal opportunities for inclusion—into the status of membership across a wide range of societal institutions. Corresponding to the normative relationship between human rights and social justice suggested in this discussion, increasingly human rights are treated as the primary political mechanism for addressing this general instance of injustice in the distribution of opportunities for disable persons to be full members of a political society. As in the case of previous iterations of the emergence of human rights practices, the human rights of disabled persons begins at the level of international conventions, with the Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities (CRPD) coming into force into 2008 (Weller 2009). Reflecting the idea of membership protections, the CRPD adopts a ‘social model of disability’ that brings together at a high level the interconnected sources of the social exclusion and marginalization of persons with disabilities, articulating broad categories of rights, including non-discrimination equality, equality rights and rights associated with social participation. The articles of the CRPD begin by establishing disabled persons as appropriate subjects of rights, moves to addressing barriers of exclusion and ends with positive entitlement claims to aspects of active social participation. Following the enactment of the CRPD, and following the broad trend of twenty-first century human rights practice, instances of “translating abstract principles of human rights into the content of domestic law” began to occur (Weller 2009, p. 7). Thus, the CPRD is an effective example of the nested nature of the normativity Laws 2017, 6, 7 7 of 16 of social justice and human. Human rights are nested in general principles of social justice, like fair equality of opportunity, that are designed to regulate the overall institutional structure of a political society. Such principles are used to evaluate specific kinds of unjust opportunity inequality and generate human rights mechanisms that identify subjects of rights, and particular sources of exclusion. Moving from international convention to domestic legislation and jurisdiction, human rights norms are applied to concrete institutional dynamics and interactions. In the case of CPRD, we see abstract rights claims in international conventions eventually filter down to re-evaluations of legislative entitlements, including as fine-grained applications as reforming empowerments of health care providers and patients at the level of treatment delivery (Weller 2009). To wrap up this section, theorizing human rights as mechanism for protections against exclusion from political membership has two primary implications for their normative structure that bring them closer to the idea of social justice. The first is that human rights, conceptualized as membership norms, are comparative, rather than baseline standards of protection and inclusion. This is so because one’s status as a member depends on relational aspects of one’s relative standing to the procedural and substantive conditions of a political society that form the general expectations of membership in that society. The second implication is that human rights as membership norms are dynamic, and not necessarily standardized across societies because, as the general conditions of society evolve, the requirements of inclusion in that society similarly change. This stands in contrast to the less dynamic nature of common protections against standard associative threats that ground human rights in the dominant philosophical view. The following section considers how a normative model of human rights that is continuous with the egalitarianism of social justice fits in with what is widely seen as the principal political function of human rights as establishing and satisfying the conditions of political legitimacy. In so doing, it addresses a central claim of the discontinuous view that an egalitarian conception of human rights is incompatible with at basic aspect of human rights practice of establishing the normative requirements of the legitimacy of states. 4. Membership and Political Legitimacy The status of membership distinguishes between subjection to imposed political coordination and an ideal of voluntary social cooperation. While different kinds of systems of subjection can remain stable through the effective exercise of domination, without respect for membership, such societies can be said to lack normative political legitimacy. Developing the idea of membership, this section aims to show that an egalitarian normative model of human rights that shares normative space with social justice does not require abandoning the primary aspect of current human rights practice of establishing political legitimacy, though it does entail a particular conception of legitimacy. The function of securing political legitimacy is central to the ‘justifying purpose’ of human rights in the dominant approach, and a primary ground for discontinuity between the normative domains of human rights and social justice. The focus, however, is principally placed on international, recognitional, legitimacy. As Raz puts it, “while human rights are invoked in various contexts, and for a variety for purposes, the dominant trend in human rights practice is to take the fact that a right is a human right as a defeasibly sufficient ground for taking action against violators in the international arena, that is to take its violation as a reason for such action” (Raz 2010, p. 9; see also Rawls 1999b and Beitz 2009). This conception of the role of human rights in political legitimacy ties into other features of the dominant normative view. One is the universalism of the content of human rights required to establish a shared international standard for the “limits to state sovereignty” (Raz 2010). Another is the relative minimalism of the concept of human rights as common protections against standard associative threats, needed for both respecting the value of sovereignty itself and for respecting the value of toleration of diverse, though recognizably legitimate, forms of political arrangements. The final section of this paper will return to the issue of how the status of human rights Laws 2017, 6, 7 8 of 16 as matters of international concern may limit their egalitarianism; however, the focus for now will be on establishing the role of human rights in domestic processes of political legitimacy. All violations of legitimacy need not be understood as mapping onto the “limits to state sovereignty,” and as the trigger of interventionist action. International, recognitional, legitimacy therefore does not exhaust the role of human rights in political legitimacy, as it has internal dimensions that apply in the first instance to the interests, attitudes and behaviours of persons with respect to the institutional arrangements that govern them. Given this, the dominant philosophical view of human rights is not a satisfactory conception of the constraints and requirements on institutions that would constitute the interests of those governed by them, if they are to have their membership interests respected. Because of the possibility of different ways of organizing governing institutions, persons can reasonably expect terms of justification and forms of inclusion that go beyond maintaining common protections against standard threats created by political power, as conditions to accept as legitimate ‘the disciplines and burdens’ of membership. In current political practice, these deeper justificatory claims are increasingly made in the language of human rights, building up their egalitarian standing, and bringing them closer to the normativity of justice. It may be objected that the cost of a more egalitarian conception of human rights, nested in the requirements of social justice, is that it becomes an inappropriate standard of internal legitimacy as it will be too demanding to be a realistically achievable condition of political legitimacy. This concern informs, for instance, Cohen’s distinction between human rights as baseline membership norms of political legitimacy and social justice as a more maximalist ideal for social cooperation—“the rights that are required if individuals are to treated as members would be identical to the right that are required if the requirements imposed by law and other regulations are to genuine obligations . . . (and treating these rights as human rights is) . . . certainly more plausible than a theory of obligation that ties political obligation to justice” (Cohen 2010, p. 329). Thus, if human rights are to function as the condition of domestic legitimacy, their content needs to be limited to a feasible point for persons to accept and act on the types of obligations necessary for political stability. Against this ground for distinguishing between human rights and social justice is the possibility of a conception of legitimacy as principled support and stability that does not appeal to correlative moral obligations of compliance (Green 1988; Parekh 1993). Rather than producing stability through acquired obligations, an alternative, non-obligatory, conception of legitimacy includes a more diffuse range of attitudes and behaviours. On Charles Taylor’s view, “a society has legitimacy when members so understand and value it that they are willing to assume the disciplines and burdens which membership entails” (Taylor 1993, pp. 64–65). Political stability based on normative legitimacy is, then, “distinguishable from purely self-interest or instrumental behavior on the one hand, and from straightforward imposed or coerced rule on the other” (Hurrell 2005, p. 16). Legitimacy, on such a view, is not an ‘either-or’ scenario, but is an ongoing dynamic of contestation and the formation of pluralistic beliefs and commitments that signify acceptance or rejection of institutional arrangements and their regulative principles. Rawls presents a similar rendering of the concept in suggesting that legitimacy amounts to political stability “for the right reasons” (Rawls 1993, p. 391); that is, when members accept its proffered terms of justification, and support its institutions based on perceptions of generally sufficient satisfaction of these terms in its functioning. Human rights and social justice, operating at different levels of abstraction from political practice, can be seen to establish what Rawls calls a ‘range of legitimacy’ (Rawls 1993, p. 428). Certain types of inequalities and exclusions are necessarily ruled out of this range as baseline conditions of legitimation; it should not, however, be treated as static and leaves significant space for democratic deliberation and social choice as to the cooperative ends to be pursued and the appropriate regulative principles for the distribution of relevant cooperative burdens and benefits. Political legitimacy, of course, is a deeply contested concept, and this paper does not seek to argue in favour of a particular conception. The aim here is instead to consider how a particular, non-obligatory, conception of legitimacy creates theoretical space for an egalitarian normative model Laws 2017, 6, 7 9 of 16 of human rights. Thinking of legitimacy as a dynamic range of institutional requirements for the justified exercise of authority establishes political openings for deepened practices of human rights and social justice. Through contestation and demands for reform, previously tolerated forms of exclusionary barriers to membership can be ruled out of subsequent demarcations of the range of legitimacy. Human rights activism, iteration of human rights norms and consolidation of deepened institutionalized human rights protections have the effect of altering standards of legitimacy by, as Seyla Benhabib puts it, raising “the threshold of justification to which formerly exclusionary practices are now submitted” (Benhabib 2006, p. 60). Normative standards of legitimacy should therefore not be treated as fixed, as in the case that ties it to a conception of human rights as common protections against standard associative threats. The requirements of legitimacy are, rather, responsive to institutional formation and changing forms of political discourse and activism, and so, as Jeffrey Reiman argues, “we cannot take for granted that any existing formulation of (legitimacy’s) conditions is complete . . . a government must do more than merely keep within some identified set of conditions . . . (it) must be continually monitoring the conditions of its legitimacy and effectively correcting existing formulations of these conditions” (Reiman 1997, p. 127). With this dynamic understanding of political legitimacy, a key way in which equality emerges in the world is when the legitimacy of the exercise of political power is challenged by those subjected to it who oppose barriers of exclusion it establishes and perpetuates (Nagel 2005, pp. 146–47). Such demands are increasingly made in the language of human rights. In this sense, human rights are not merely a given set of formalized protections and immunities, but also function as the language of contestation and aspiration for deepened practices of inclusionary membership in the institutional arrangements that govern people. 5. Human Rights as Aspirational Building on the link between human rights as membership norms and iterative processes of the development of the standards of political legitimacy, this section further develops overlapping points of normativity between human rights and social justice in their functioning as principles of social aspiration in the contestation of power by individuals and groups. In this respect, human rights are not only existing protections against exclusions from the status of membership, but are also, in part, constitutive of expectations for further inclusion held in its name. It is suggested that human rights increasingly overlap with the language of citizenship rights in grounding inclusionary claims of justice in particular institutional settings. The discursive elements of human rights practice in which novel demands for social inclusion are made through the language of human rights, human rights function not just to meet the requirements of legitimacy, but also to define and reconfigure them moving forward. The aspirational quality of principles of social justice is relatively straightforward given their status as general principles (e.g., fair equality of opportunity) that function in the deep background of the institutional structure of a political society. Human rights, on the other hand, operating, as has been suggested, as specific manifestations of principles of social justice in particular settings as concrete claim rights are often theorized as ‘mandatory norms’ limited by the identification of specific duty-bearers, which often has the effect of limiting equality rights in socioeconomic areas (Nickel 2007, pp. 31–35). Though it is the case that human rights are often operationalized as formal juridical and legislative entitlements imposing correlative duties on domestic and international institutional agents, it is important to recognize that an equally significant, and perhaps prior, aspect of human rights practice is that of framing aspirations for reforming exclusionary barriers to a dynamic ideal of membership that can give rise to juridical and legislative change. Theorizing this dimension of the concept of human rights, while deepening their egalitarianism, also addresses the standard concerns of egalitarian conceptions of human rights of inflationary infeasibility and democratic acceptability within political pluralism. Amartya Sen’s theory of human rights exhibits this dualistic political role for human rights. Like principles of social justice, human rights do frequently function as “inspiration for legislation” and help Laws 2017, 6, 7 10 of 16 to illuminate the “legislative route” towards greater inclusion (Sen 2009, pp. 363–64). However, in many cases, the legislative route is not always open, or the most appropriate path, for human rights, but, as Sen puts it, “(b)ecause of the importance of communication, advocacy, exposure and informed public discussion, human rights can have influence without necessarily depending on coercive legislation” (Sen 2009, p. 365). Informal routes of the influence of human rights work by altering, institutionally and discursively, the general conditions of political legitimacy and the ‘threshold of exclusion’ in subsequent law and legislation. Human rights are, in this functioning, closer to Joel Feinberg’s idea of socioeconomic rights as ‘manifesto rights’—broad and dynamic expectations and aspirations for entitlement that condition institutional formation—than a conception of rights as mandatory norms consisting of claims against concrete duty-bearers. As aspirational norms, human rights operate to establish general expectations with respect to the functioning of institutional systems, and function politically “as determinants of present aspirations and guides to present policy” (Feinberg 1973, p. 67). Understanding human rights in this way suggests compelling similarities in their functioning to citizenship rights as a core mechanism of deepened practices of social justice. In T.H. Marshall’s foundational view of the egalitarianism of citizenship, the primary function of citizenship rights, rather than setting formal entitlement, is to condition the salient social ideas, experiences and expectations that condition the legitimacy requirements of states. Citizenship right, he argues, represents a “principle of equality” that functions ideally against “structural inequality.” Juridical and legislative entitlement embodying citizenship’s principle of equality, “instead of being the decisive step that puts policy into immediate effect, acquires more and more the character of a declaration of policy that it is hoped to put into effect some day” (Marshall 1964, p. 104). Institutional treatment and entitlement reflecting the equality of citizenship affects the “superstructure of legitimate expectations” held by members and functions as a normative standard of inclusion that “is perpetually moving forward” (Marshall 1964, p. 115). Thus, according to Marshall, “societies in which citizenship is a developing institution create an image of an ideal citizenship against which achievement can be measured and which aspiration can be directed” (Marshall 1964, p. 84). An aspirational view of human rights understands their political functioning as an additional normative layer to the equality of citizenship that can further condition the legitimacy requirements of institutional development towards egalitarian justice. Reflection on current human rights practice suggests a primary function of human rights is to work as critical taming norms for the status of citizenship in particular societies by providing external egalitarian grounds to contest different features of its condition. As Jeremy Waldron notes, there is increasingly an “interesting duplication of the subject matter between cosmopolitan norms and rules of municipal law,” such that human rights function as critical “ideas about how municipal law should be changed” (Waldron 2006, pp. 85–86). Kymlicka develops a similar claim about the relationship between human rights and citizenship, whereby the former works as ‘inspiration’ for the inclusionary tendencies of states’ treatment of historically excluded groups in traditional practices of citizenship. He argues that, “the trend towards liberal multiculturalism can only be understood as a new stage in the gradual working out of the logic of human rights, and in particular the logic of the idea of the inherent equality of human beings” (Kymlicka 2007, p. 89). While inspiring new multicultural forms of treatment of minority groups within states, Kymlicka makes the further claim that human rights also function to ‘constrain’ contestation of citizenship, as with the ascendancy of the language of human rights, “there is no legal space for minorities to set aside human rights norms in the name of multiculturalism, and, in the case of most minorities, there is no wish to do so” (Kymlicka 2007, p. 93). The addition of human rights as a further layer of regulative principles for the development of institutions may be seen as a welcome development from the liberal perspective because of the more explicit disconnection of aspirational ideas of equality from historically exclusionary bases of citizenship, such as nationality and ethnicity, which limited its capacity as a mechanism of justice. Incorporation of human rights into the ideational character of membership in political associations helps to ‘loosen’ the connections between more or less closed identities and citizenship solidarity and, Laws 2017, 6, 7 11 of 16 as Spinner-Halev suggests, allows states to more easily “turn to the needs of their minority groups” (Spinner-Halev 2008, p. 615). A common criticism of an aspirational and informal understanding of the egalitarian dimensions of human rights (and indeed of citizenship rights) is that it potentially weakens the practice by diminishing the key conceptual dimension of a right as a claim against specific, capable, duty-bearers (Kymlicka 2002; Spinner-Halev 2008). According to Nickel, the structure of human rights as ‘mandatory norms’ in political development includes both entitlement claims and obligations as “modes of directing the behaviour of the addressees” (Nickel 2007, pp. 30–31). The requirement of concrete duty-bearers, with sufficient capacities, he argues, protects against expansion of entitlement beyond present material and motivational capacities which weakens the political practice of human rights. Under the concept of human rights as membership norms that function in processes of political legitimacy, however, the inflationary possibility that attends human rights as aspirational norms is less of a concern, and is indeed a welcomed source of dynamism. Human rights should be sensitive to changing conditions of membership and be adaptable to the kinds of exclusions that prevent persons from achieving membership status. While there are general kinds of membership interests that transcend context, many are dynamic, subsequent ideas that cannot be easily understood when abstracted from the relevant political association’s unique patterns of producing and distributing burdens and benefits. What membership requires in one time and place may be substantially different than in others. In this respect, dynamism and inflation are necessary components of a theory of human rights as membership norms. While endorsing a dynamic conception of the content of human rights, grounding them in the interests of membership does impose limits on inflation beyond existent institutional and resource capacities. Though membership is an ideal and aspirational status of inclusion, it is based in the actual range of burdens and benefits that constitute the reasonable expectations of membership in particular political societies. In making inclusionary claims, a responsibility of membership is formulating them in line with the reasonable expectations of membership and present resource availability (Buchanan 2010, p. 187). This can largely be expected to be the standard case with human rights claims as they tend to be directed towards forms of exclusion to institutional opportunities that shape the expectations of most members. They will be generally feasible since to be reasonable expectations of membership, they will already be secured for most persons. Theorizing human rights as aspirational norms of membership also addresses the common criticism that holds that an egalitarian and expansive conception of human rights undercuts the idea of universality and introduces a justificatory concern of parochialism. On this objection, in light of the deep diversity across and within political societies, human rights, as standards of legitimate exercise of political authority, should be relatively minimal and uncontroversial across a wide range of ethical and moral doctrines. Expanding the sites of exclusion that are concerns of human rights, and expanding the kinds of human rights instruments that are available to address them, it is argued, can introduce tensions between human rights as acceptable standards of legitmacy and ideals of toleration and self-determination of reasonably diverse societal cultures (Cohen 2010, pp. 343–47). However, theorizing human rights as aspirational norms of inclusion into the constitutive institutions and practices of membership in a particular society, rather than as formally required universal standards for all societies, helps to reconcile an egalitarian conception of human rights with the values of self-determination and endogenous emergence of regulative norms. As aspirational standards of inclusion, human rights are available to a wide range of interests that stem from the material and cultural particulars of different forms of political association. Contextualized human rights claims can be seen in this sense as re-iterations of universal ideals of inclusion that are appropriately sensitive to the condition of membership in specific settings. As Benhabib characterizes the iterative dynamic of the universal idea of human rights in ways that reconcile it with the self-determination of particular value structures, the “iteration and interpretation of norms . . . is never merely an act of repetition. Every iteration involves making sense of an authoritative original in a new and different context” Laws 2017, 6, 7 12 of 16 (Benhabib 2006, pp. 46–50). This view of the role of universal human rights norms in shaping the conditions of legitimacy in particular political societies, moves the concept of legitimacy away from a formal conception of standardized protections and entitlements towards an ongoing deliberative conception “creative appropriation” of human rights in particular sites of political membership. Theorizing human rights in this way has the effect, as Jeremy Waldron suggest, of “shifting out attention away from formal democratic legitimacy to the more demotic legitimacy of ordinary iteration . . . (and so) we need not be as pre-occupied as we are . . . with borders and the scope of norms. Norms emerge in the world in the circumstances of dense interactions that occur all over the place (and are) democratic simply in the demotic dailiness of (their) use” (Waldron 2006, pp. 97–98). As aspirational norms for inclusion as a member of a political society, human rights emerge and exist in the world as universally available grounds for principled criticism, contestation and reform that can be adopted and applied to conditions of membership as they are found and understood. 6. International Concern The discussion of the egalitarian nature of social justice and human rights as nested membership norms in processes of establishing and satisfying the conditions of political legitimacy has thus far been domestic in its orientation. As mentioned, however, the primary approach to theorizing human rights as conditions of legitimacy concerns the terms of international recognitional legitimacy. The idea of human rights as international concern is widely thought to be a critical piece of an adequate conception of human rights, and one that marks it off from the normative domain of social justice (see, for example, (Beitz 2009; Rawls 1999b; Raz 2010; Risse 2012)). Human rights, on this view, while applying to the relationship between the institutions of political association and its members, are marked off from other political norms for association by being, further, standards of justification the violation of which imposes obligations of assistance on non-members. They are not, then, purely membership norms but are matters of international concern that make claims on the resources and capacities of non-members in ways that social justice does not. As Raz formulates the distinction, what makes a right a human right is that it is a right against one’s government that is “assertible in the international arena” and that its violation is “a (defeasible) reason for taking action against violators in the international arena . . . (such that) . . . (d)isabling the defence ‘none of your business’, is definitive of the political conception of human rights” (Raz 2010, pp. 328–32). With this distinctive function, human rights will fall short of the rights of social justice, as not all violations of social justice trigger international concern. Charles Beitz has fully developed this ground for distinguishing between the normativity of human rights and social justice, and this section responds to two of his arguments for this position. Beitz’s theory of human rights identifies the idea of international concern as a constitutive element of its normative structure that marks it off from social justice. He presents a three-part conception of human rights: human rights protect interests that are sufficiently important to make their protection a ‘political priority’; they apply to states as duties and it is advantageous for persons that states work to protect the underlying interests; and, the failure to protect the relevant interests in a ‘range of cases’ is a ‘suitable object of international concern’ (Beitz 2009, p. 136). Human rights, in this view, while applying to the relationship between the institutions of political association and its members, are marked off from other political norms for association by being, further, standards of justification the violation of which imposes obligations of assistance on non-members. They are not, then, purely membership norms but are matters of international concern that make claims on the resources and capacities of non-members in ways that social justice does not. International concern, it is important to note, includes a range of non-coercive ‘paradigms of implementation’, such as, ‘accountability’, ‘inducement’, ‘assistance’, ‘domestic contestation and engagement’, ‘compulsion’, and ‘external adaptation’ (Beitz 2009, pp. 33–40). This leads to a conception of human rights that is not ‘minimalist’ (because of the expansive non-coercive view of concern and intervention), but is not Laws 2017, 6, 7 13 of 16 ‘maximalist’ in the sense of overlapping with the full domain of social justice due to other limiting considerations of international concern. The constitutive idea of international concern in a concept of human rights, according to Beitz, marks it off from social justice for two related reasons, both of which address different issues of the capacity of international actors and the concern that “some requirements of justice may not be achievable by means of any permissible form of action available to outside agents” (Beitz 2009, p. 143). The first reason addresses limited material capacity, since “the international resources available for advancing human rights are scarce.” Given the limited resources behind international concern for human rights, it is important, Beitz argues, to distinguish and prioritize the interests underpinning human rights and social justice. Human rights, he holds, are underpinned by the more urgent non-relational interest in having a “standard of living adequate for a decent life” whereas social justice is underpinned by the comparative “interest in not feeling ashamed or humiliated by one’s material situation considered in relation to those of others” (Beitz 2009, pp. 142–43). Because there is a significant material distinction between “assisting a society to develop its economy sufficiently to eliminate the worst forms of poverty and causing it to attain an income distribution that satisfies some more ambitious standard of distributive justice” human rights should be limited to the more minimal, and apparently cheaper, aim of satisfying the requirements of a decent life (Beitz 2009, p. 143). It is not clear, however, that this objection’s framing of social justice as the stronger relationally egalitarian, and therefore more expensive, norm necessarily holds. As discussed, social justice primarily functions as regulative principles for existing political practice, and provides general standards for fair terms of inclusion into the material and cultural life of a political society. Social justice itself, in other words, does not tend to motivate social cooperation, but comes in as conditions of its normative legitimacy through processes of contestation. Actualized requirements of justice are, then, as Sangiovanni puts it, ‘practice dependent’ (Sangiovanni 2008). That is, while relational, requirements of social justice come in subsequently to institutionalized cooperation to regulate the broad distributive patterns of cooperative benefits, and to compel redistribution in cases where inequality excludes groups of persons from the status of political membership. A concept of justice as regulative principles for social cooperation will take the kinds of benefit production and development levels as found and primarily concerns interpersonal comparisons in the distribution of whatever kinds and levels of benefits are being produced. For example, in a three-person micro-case, all things being equal, a (1-1-1) distribution is just even if resource level (1) is meager and falls short of “a standard of living adequate for a decent life” (the interest Beitz identifies underpinning human rights). In this respect, human rights, as concerned with objective thresholds of well-being, not social justice, requires increasing (1) to, say, (2), which is, perhaps, more materially demanding than redistributing at the level of existing resources. One question of justice is whether the move from (1-1-1) to (8-4-2) is just, in addition to being an efficient move from the status quo. The second argument to distinguish the respective domains of human rights and social justice that Beitz makes from the “practical role of human rights as sources of reasons for transnational political action” concerns the epistemological capacity of international actors. He argues that the laws, institutions and policies of social justice can be expected to “vary across societies in ways that respond to differences in the economic, social and cultural background” and that “judgments about the requirements of justice at this level sometimes turn on complex assessments of the significance of the pertinent background facts . . . that outsiders are at a disadvantage in making” (Beitz 2009, p. 143). The membership concept of human rights suggests against this reason to distinguish it from social justice. It has been suggested that human rights and social justice are nested egalitarian norms, operating at different levels of abstraction from institutions, in establishing and satisfying the normative conditions of legitimacy in a political association. Social justice operates at a deeper level of abstraction from institutions than human rights and concerns the working of institutions together as it bears on general principles of justice, such as equal opportunity. Human rights function at more concrete levels of institutions and entitlements as mechanisms for more realizing general principles of Laws 2017, 6, 7 14 of 16 social justice. Given the function of human rights in delivering general principles of social justice in specific institutional areas, it is human rights that would seem to be necessarily more sensitive to the particularities of context, and the importance of entitlement levels in a specific area for the general structure of membership. Human rights as membership norms can be expected to display significant variation at the level of implementation based on differences across associations in the institutional and policy areas to which they apply. This should not, however, suggest against the status of human rights (or social justice) as matters of international concern, but that external forms of what Sen calls ‘social help’ (Sen 2004, p. 329) should be part of consultative processes in which relevant capacities and insights are brought to bear on the process by different domestic and international agents. Reflecting on these two arguments, the idea of non-coercive international concern does not seem decisive in setting a firm distinction between human rights and social justice, whereby human rights are the more minimalist, less egalitarian norm. A political conception of justice as subsequent regulative principles for the distribution of cooperative benefits and burdens need not require greater material or epistemological capacities on the part of international actors than a similar concept of human rights. It is also plausible that conventional concerns of comparative inequality in a theory of social justice above the threshold of decent levels of well-being can be properly seen as matters of international concern, such as in the case of significant relative inequality between a structurally advantaged majority and disadvantaged minority (or vice versa), even when the shares of the worse off is above, even well above, the preferred conception of decent or minimal levels of well-being (Griffin 2008, p. 201). 7. Conclusions Human rights practices have become a remarkably significant political force in a relatively short period of time (Raz 2010, p. 321). Increasingly, it is the dominant language of contestation of political structures and of formulating entitlement claims to different forms of institutional treatment. In this respect, human rights have not necessarily given rise to new kinds of political concerns than those addressed by claims of citizenship rights, but work to more explicitly link conventional kinds of normative claims and expectations in political associations to the universal language of the equal moral standing of humanity. Human rights connect membership claims within a political association to an external egalitarian status that bears on its legitimacy. A notable development in the continuing emergence of human rights norms is the expansion of the kinds of inequality and exclusion they cover, including both the relevant sites and identities of exclusive practices. This ongoing development increasingly brings human rights practice closer in line with forms of membership-oriented comparative evaluations that characterize a political concept of social justice than with a general idea of a socially situated minimally decent level of well-being. The basic suggestion of this paper is that the upward tendencies in the development of human rights practice need not be theoretically capped short of the principles of social justice. It aimed to show that an expansive, egalitarian, conception of human rights can be reconciled with them functioning as the basic mechanism of (a specific conception of) political legitimacy. The discursive and institutional elements of this dynamic also address concerns of inflationary concerns that attend to resource availability, as well as worries about problematic justificatory parochialism in an egalitarian normative model. It was further argued that the status of human rights, as matters of international concern, needs to be seen as decisive in ruling out an egalitarian conception of their demands. Acknowledgments: This paper was supported by a University of Saskatchewan President’s SSHRC Grant, for which I am grateful. Conflicts of Interest: The author declares no conflict of interest. References Beitz, Charles. 2009. The Idea of Human Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Laws 2017, 6, 7 15 of 16 Benhabib, Seyla. 2006. Democratic Iterations: The Local, the National and the Global. In Another Cosmopolitanism. Edited by Robert Post. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 45–82. Buchanan, Allen. 2005. Equality and Human Rights. Politics, Philosophy and Economics 4: 69–90. [CrossRef] Buchanan, Allen. 2010. The Egalitarianism of Human Rights. Ethics 120: 679–710. [CrossRef] Clapham, Andrew. 2007. Human Rights: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Cohen, Joshua. 2010. The Arc of the Moral Universe and Other Essays. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Cranston, Maurice. 1973. What are Human Rights? London: Bodley Head. Dworkin, Ronald. 1978. Taking Rights Seriously. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Feinberg, Joel. 1973. Social Philosophy. Englewood Cliff: Prentice Hall. Finnis, John. 2011. Natural Law and Natural Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Fraser, Nancy. 1996. Social Justice in the Age of Identity Politics. Salt Lake: Tanner Lectures on Human Values. Garcea, Joseph, and Neil Hibbert. 2011. Policy Frameworks for Managing Diversity in Canada. In Integration and Inclusion of Newcomers and Minorities across Canada. Edited by John Biles, Meyer Burstein, James Frideres, Erin Tolley and Rob Vineberg. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press, pp. 18–45. Gravel, Eric, and Quentin Delpech. 2008. International Labour Standards: Recent Developments in Complementarity between the International and National Supervisory Systems. International Labour Review 147: 403–15. [CrossRef] Green, Leslie. 1988. The Authority of the State. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Griffin, James. 2008. On Human Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Heath, Joseph. 2011. Three Normative Models of the Welfare State. Public Reason 3: 13–44. Hucker, John. 1997. Antidiscrimination Laws in Canada: Human Rights Commissions and the Search for Equality. Human Rights Quarterly 19: 547–71. [CrossRef] Hurrell, Andrew. 2005. Legitimacy in the Use of Force: Can the Circle be Squared? Review of International Studies 31: 15–32. [CrossRef] Jetsckhe, Anja. 1999. Linking the Unlinkable? International Norms and Nationalism in Indonesia and the Philippines. In The Power of Human Rights: International Norms & Domestic Change. Edited by Thomas Risse, Stephen C. Ropp and Kathryn Sikkink. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 134–71. Jones, Charles. 2010. Human Rights and Moral Cosmopolitanism. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 13: 115–35. [CrossRef] Kymlicka, Will. 2002. Contemporary Political Philosophy, 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Kymlicka, Will. 2007. Multicultural Odysseys. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Marshall, Thomas H. 1964. Class, Citizenship and Social Development. New York: Doubleday. Nagel, Thomas. 2005. The Problem of Global Justice. Philosophy and Public Affairs 33: 113–47. [CrossRef] Nickel, Jamie. 2007. Making Sense of Human Rights, 2nd ed. Malden: Blackwell. O’Neill, Onora. 2005. The Dark Side of Human Rights. International Affairs 81: 427–39. [CrossRef] Parekh, Bhiku. 1993. A Misconceived Discourse on Political Obligation. Political Studies 41: 236–51. [CrossRef] Rawls, John. 1993. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press. Rawls, John. 1999a. A Theory of Justice, 2nd ed. Cambridge: Belknap Press. Rawls, John. 1999b. The Law of Peoples. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Ray, Douglas, and Norma Bernstein Tarrow. 2014. Human Rights and Education: An Overview. In Human Rights and Education, 3rd ed. Edited by N. Berstein Tarrow. New York: Pergamon Press, pp. 3–16. Raz, Joseph. 2010. Human Rights without Foundations. In The Philosophy of International Law. Edited by Samantha Besson and John Tasioulas. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 321–38. Reiman, Jeffrey. 1997. Critical Moral Liberalism. New York: Rowman and Littlefield. Risse, Mathias. 2012. On Global Justice. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Sangiovanni, Andrea. 2008. Justice and the Priority of Politics to Morality. Journal of Political Philosophy 16: 137–64. [CrossRef] Sen, Amartya. 2004. Elements of a Theory of Human Rights. Philosophy and Public Affairs 32: 315–56. [CrossRef] Sen, Amartya. 2009. The Idea of Justice. Cambridge: Belknap Press. Spinner-Halev, Jeffrey. 2008. Democracy, Solidarity and Post-Nationalism. Political Studies 56: 604–28. [CrossRef] Taylor, Charles. 1993. Reconciling the Solitudes. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press. UN General Assembly. 1948. Universal Declaration of Human Rights. New York: UN General Assembly. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/1470594X05049436 http://dx.doi.org/10.1086/653433 http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1564-913X.2008.00042.x http://dx.doi.org/10.1353/hrq.1997.0028 http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0260210505006765 http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/13698230903326299 http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.2005.00027.x http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-2346.2005.00459.x http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.2006.tb00926.x http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9760.2007.00291.x http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.2004.00017.x http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.2007.00708.x Laws 2017, 6, 7 16 of 16 Vizard, Polly. 2006. Poverty and Human Rights: Sen’s Capability Perspective Explored. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Waldron, Jeremy. 2006. Cosmopolitan Norms. In Another Cosmopolitanism. Edited by Robert Post. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 83–101. Weller, Penelope. 2009. Human Rights and Social Justice: the CRPD and the Quiet Revolution in International Law. Public Space: The Journal of Law and Social Justice 4: 74–91. © 2017 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/). http://creativecommons.org/ http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/. Introduction The Dominant Philosophical View of Human Rights and Social Justice Human Rights as Membership Norms Membership and Political Legitimacy Human Rights as Aspirational International Concern Conclusions work_3huqvrglnjcmjap3vww3bxwqni ---- CANADIAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY Supplement Volume VII, 1981 Doing Marx Justice GARY YOUNG, Madison, Wisconsin The circumstance that on the one hand the daily sustenance of labour power costs only half a day's labor, while on the other hand the very same labor power can work during a whole day, that consequently the value which its use during one day creates is double what he [the capitalist] pays for that use, this circumstance is without a doubt a piece of good luck for the buyer but by no means an injustice [UnrechtJ to the seller [the worker}.1 [TJhe surplus product [is] the tribute annually exacted from the working class by the capitalist class. Though the latter with a portion of that tribute purchases the additional labor power even at its full price, so that equivalent is exchanged for equivalent, yet the transaction is for all that only the old dodge of every conqueror who buys commodities from the conquered with the money he has robbed them of. 2 Was Marx confused? How could he think what these passages and others like them say: that the capitalist robs the worker but treats the worker justly? Marx's statements make sense only if the contradiction between robbery and justice is merely apparent. There are three ways to show that it is. Each has been defended recently. Karl Marx, Capital (New York: 1967) 1,194. 2 Ibid. 582. 251 Gary Young First, one can say that Marx does not mean 'rob' in the ordinary sense in which robbery without qualification is unjust. Derek P.H. AUen and Allen W. Wood have advocated this interpretation.) Second, one can say that Marx does not mean 'unjust' in the or­ dinary sense in which it is unjust to rob. Ziyad I. Husami has defended this interpretation. 4 Third, one can say that Marx meant 'rob' and 'unjust' in their or­ dinary senses, but that he was referring to two distinct transactions when he said the worker is robbed but treated justly. In an earlier papers I took this position. I contended that on Marx's view the worker is treated justly as seller in the exchange of tabor power for wages, but is then robbed in the production process, during which the capitalist extracts surplus value from the worker. I further argued that on Marx's view only the extraction of surplus value, not the wage exchange, is real. In reality, therefore, capitalist production is wholly unjust. I still think this third position is right, despite vigorous defenses of the others by Wood, Allen and Husami. In what foflows 1 shall sketch a defense of my position against Allen's and Wood's main points. Sec­ tions I and 11 examine the justice of the wage-exchange and injustice of capitalist exploitation, looking first at texts where Marx speaks of justice (Section I) and then texts where he speaks of theft (Section II). Section III develops the latter theme by turning to Marx's assessment of primitive capitalist accumulation as theft. Section IV reconsiders Marx's view that the wage-exchange is not real. In the final section, I discuss Marx's use of the concepts of justice and freedom to criticize capitalist production relations. 3 Derek P.H. Allen, 'Marx and Engels on the Distributive Justice of Capitalism,' this volume, 221 MSO, Allen W. Wood, 'The Marxian Critique of Justice,' Philosophy & Public Affairs 1 (1971-2) 244-82 (cited as Wood [1 ]); 'Marx on Right and Justice: A Reply to Husami,' Philosophy and Public Affairs 8 (1978-9) 267-95 (cited as Wood [2]). 4 Ziyad I. Husami, 'Marx on Distributive Justice,' Philosophy & Public Affairs 8 {1978-9) 27-64. 5 Gary Young, 'Justice and Capitalist Production: Marx and Bourgeois Ideology,' Canadian Journal of Philosophy 8 (1978) 421-55. 252 Doing Marx Justice Allen and Wood argue that Marx regarded the extraction of surplus value as just. They draw this inference from two distinct sorts of statements in Marx's writings. Illustrative of the first sort of statement is that quoted at the start of this paper, in which Marx says that the creation of surplus value during direct production 'is without a doubt a piece of good luckfor the buyer [of labour power, namely the capitalist] but by no means an injustice to the seller [the worker].'6 From such passages Allen and Wood infer that the extraction of surplus value is not unjust to the worker, who is, after all, the seller of labor power. But this inference is unwarranted, in the sense in which Allen and Wood intend it. In these passages Marx is speaking of the worker only in his or her role as owner and seller of labor power, not as a factor in the production process. In his or her role as seHer, the worker is treated fairly, because (Marx assumes) the worker receives in the form of wages the value of the labor power he or she sells. But this leaves it an open question whether the worker is treated fairly as factor in the process of production. Marx answers this question in the negative, as passages discussed in the next section show. To understand fully what Marx means when he says that the seller of labor power is not treated unjustly, we must recall the crucial importan­ ce in Marx's analysis of capitalist production of the distinction between exchange or circulation and direct production. 7 To this distinction corresponds another between two roles taken by the worker. In the marketplace, the worker appears as the owner of his or her own labor power; bargaining, the worker appears as potential seller of labor power, and when the sale is executed, as actual seller. But once the sale is completed, the worker is no longer owner or selJer of labor power: The worker is now nothing but labor power for use in production (for the duration of the term of sale), and moreover labor power owned by the capitalist. Marx says the worker is now a 'living component of capital.' The apparently symmetrical relation of buyer and seller in the market is now replaced by the asymmetrical relation of owner and owned. This transformation occurs because what the worker as seller sells is the worker as labor power. 'The worker' is ambiguous between these two distinct roles. This ambiguity underlies not only the invalid in­ 6 Capital I, 194. 7 See my /The Fundamental Contradiction of Capitalist Production,' Philosophy & Public Affairs 5 (1975-6) 196-234, especially 217-26. 253 Gary Young ference drawn by Allen and Wood, but also much of bourgeois ideology, as Marx explains repeatedly. We have seen that the transformation of money into capital breaks down into two wholly distinct, autonomous spheres, two entirely separate processes. The first belongs to the realm of the circulation of commodities and is acted out in the market-place. It is the sale and purchase of labour-power. The second is the consumption of the labour-power that has been acquired, i.e. the process of production itself. In the first process the capitalist and the worker confront one another merely as the owners respectively of money and commodities, and their transactions, like those of all buyers and sellers, are the exchange of equivalents. In the second process the worker appears pro tempore as the living component of capital itself, and the category of exchange is entirely excluded here since the capitalist has acquired by purchase all the factors of the produc­ tion process, both material and personal, before the negotiations begin. However, although the two processes subsist independently side by side, each conditions the other. The first introduces the second and the second completes the first. The first process, the sale and purchase of labour-power, displays to us the capitalist and the worker only as the buyer and seller of commodities. What distinguishes the worker from the vendors of other commodities is only the specific nature, the specific use-value, of the commodity he sells. But the par­ ticular use-value of a commodity does not affect the economic form of the transaction; it does not alter the fact that the purchaser represents money, and the vendor a commodity. In order to demonstrate, therefore, that the relation­ ship between capitalist and worker is nothing but a relationship between commodity owners who exchange money and commodities with a free con­ tract and to their mutual advantage, it suffices to isolate the first process and to cleave to its formal character. This simple device is no sorcery, but it contains the entire wisdom of the vulgar economists." This same point is made more colorfully by a pair of passages stan­ ding at the beginning and the end of Marx's analysis of the workday in Volume I of Capital: The sphere of circulation or the exchange of commodities, within whose boun­ daries the sale and purchase of labor power goes in, is in fact a very Eden of innate human rights. Here alone rule freedom, equality, property and Bentham .... Equality! Because they [buyer and seller) are related to each other only as owners of commodities and exchange equivalent for equivalent. On leaving this sphere of simple circulation or commodity exchange ... it seems that the physiognomy of our dramatis personae changes. The erstwhile money­ owner strides in front as capitalist, and the former owner of labour power follows him as his laborer. 9 8 Karl Marx, 'Results of the Immediate Process of Production,' in Capital I (New York: 1977) 1002. 9 Capital I, 176. 254 Doing Marx Justice It must be acknowledged that our laborer comes out of the process of pro­ duction other than he entered. In the market he stood as owner of the commod­ ity labor power over other commodity owners ... The bargain concluded, it is that he was no "free " that the time for which he is free to sell his labor power is the time for is forced to sell it, that in fact the vampire will not lose its hold on him lisa long as there is a muscle, a nerve, a drop of blood to be exploited." 10 As these statements show, we may not infer from Marx's ascription of some characteristic to the worker as seller that Marx would ascribe that same to the worker as 'living component of capital' or without qualification. But this is just the sort of inference Allen and Wood draw. They infer from Marx's statement that the worker is treated justly as seller that Marx thinks the worker is treated justly simpliciter. Moreover Marx is careful to indicate that any claim that the capitalist treats the worker justly derives from consideration of the sphere of ex­ alone, not direct production. Marx says that the 'seller' of labour power is not defrauded,11 and that the rights of the capitalist arise from the fact that he has 'bought' labor power. 12 Allen and Wood lose sight of the possibility that the distribution of value via the mechanism of the market might be just, even though the means by which value initially enters the market, and the underlying distribution of the rneans of production, is unjust. This possibility invalidates the inference from market justice to justice in direct produc­ tion or capitalist production as a whole. A similar error vitiates Allen and Wood's interpretation of the second sort of passage from which they infer that Marx thought the extraction of surolus value In of sort Marx says or that trans- are just if correspond to the dominant production relations, and unjust if contradict them. 13 But as I noted in my earlier article, the transactions Marx speaks of in these passages are ex­ pressly said to have the juridical form of a contract. They are exchange transactions which occur in the market. The extraction of surplus value is not an It occurs in direct production. Moreover, as I also noted earlier, it not intelligible to say that the extraction of surplus 10 11 12 13 Ibid. 301 ~2. [bid. 585. Ibid. 196. Karl Marx, Karl Marx: (New York: 1967) III, Writings, ed. David l-oYn 'Critique of The Gotha Prog h::lrh (New York: 1974) III, 344. ram,' 255 Gary Young value 'corresponds to' capitalist production relations; rather, it is the basic capitalist production relation. For both reasons, the second sort of passage does not imply that extraction of surplus value is just. In sum, neither sort of passage cited by Allen and Wood shows that Marx thought the extraction of surplus value just. And other passages, which they misread, show that Marx clearly thought it unjust. To these I now turn. II Wood and Allen admit that Marx says the worker is robbed by the capitalist, but they deny that it follows that Marx thought the extraction of surplus value unjust. They attempt to rebut this inference in two ways. First, Allen argues that in some of the places where Marx speaks of robbery he is referring to the robbery not of surplus value but of something else. Second, Allen and Wood contend that in other places Marx uses the word 'robbery' rhetorically, without the normal im­ plication that the act so described is unjust. Neither contention is plausible. First consider the three texts which Allen claims refer to the robbery of something other than surplus value. (a) In the Grundrisse Marx says that wealth in bourgeois society is based on 'theft [Diebstahl] of alien labor time.'14 Allen comments: 'His [Marx's] point, as the context shows, is that in capitalism the worker is 14 Karl Marx, Grundrisse (New York: 1974) 704-5. Marx says: to the degree that large industry develops, the creation of real wealth comes to depend less on labour time and on the arnount of labour employed than on the power of the agencies set in motion during labour time, whose "powerful effectiveness" is itself in turn out of all proportion to the direct labour time spent on their production, but depends rather on the general state of science and on the progress of technology, or the application of this science to production ... The theft of alien labour time, on which the present wealth is based, appears a miserable foundation in face of this new one, created by large-scale industry itself. As soon as labour in the direct form has ceased to be the great well-spring of wealth, labour time ceases and must cease to be its measure, and hence exchange value [must cease to be the measure] of use value. The surplus labour of the mass has ceased to be the condition for the development of general wealth, just as the non-labour of the few, for the development of the general powers of the human head. 256 Doing Marx Justice deprived of time for his own development.'ls No doubt this is one of Marx's points here. But a fair reading shows that Marx had another point: The extraction of surplus value is theft. This text unmistakably identifies 'alien labor time' with 'the surplus labor of the mass.' It is precisely this surplus labor, which in capitalist production takes the form of surplus value, that the capitalist steals, according to this text. (b) Marx describes the capitalist's greed for surplus labor as a 'blind eagerness for plunder [blinde Raubgier].'16 Allen comments: 'He [Marx] is referring to capital's limitless draining of labor-power, not specifically to the appropriation of surplus value.'17 But the title of the section in which this passage occurs is 'The Greed for Surplus Labor,' and the paragraph at issue expressly relates to that theme. It describes the Fac­ tory Acts as an expression of the capitalist's greed for surplus labor, which in capitalist production takes the form of surplus value. No doubt the 'blind eagerness for plunder' - that is, for surplus value - is harmful to the health of the worker ('tears up by the roots the living force of the nation'). But the direct object of the capitalist's greed is not the health of the worker, but surplus labor or value (which appears to the capitalist as profit). It is because the capitalist steals surplus value that he also steals the health of the worker. (c) Marx says that 'all progress in capitalistic agriculture is a progress in the art, not only of robbing [berauben] the laborer, but of robbing the soil; all progress in increasing the fertility of the soil for a given time is progress towards ruining the lasting sources of that fertility.'18 Allen 15 Allen, Appendix (3), 248. 16 Capital I, 238-9. Marx says: If the Reglement organique of the Danubian provinces was a positive expression of the greed for surplus-labour which every paragraph lega­ lized, the English Factory Acts are the negative expression of the same greed. These acts curb the passion of capital for a limitless draining of labour-power, by forcibly limiting the working-day by state regulations, made by a state that is ruled by capitalist and landlord. Apart from the working-class movement that daily grew more threatening, the limiting of factory labour was dictated by the same necessity which spread guano over the English fields. The same blind eagerness for plunder that in the one case exhausted the soil, had, in the other, torn up by the roots the living force of the nation. Periodical epidemics speak on this point as clearly as the diminishing military standard in Germany and France. 17 Allen, Appendix (1), 248. 18 Capital I, 506. 257 Gary Young claims that Marx speaks here of the robbery of only the worker's health. 19 Of course Marx has at least this in mind. As the two passages just discussed show, however, when Marx speaks of theft from the worker he has in mind not merely or primarily the theft of health or disposable time, but the theft of surplus value or labor. The emphasis upon the worker's health in this text hardly shows that Marx did not also mean to refer to the theft of surplus value. Indeed, it is hard to see how Marx could have regarded the taking of the worker's health or time for development as unjust and not thought the same of the taking of surplus value. But what if Allen were right, and in this text (unlike the preceding two) Marx were not referring to the theft of surplus value? Does Allen maintain that the theft of the worker's time or health is just? Doesn't this text show at least that on Marx's view capitalist production essentially involves the theft of the worker's time and health, and is for that reason unjust? I now turn to the other texts, which Allen and Wood say employ the word 'rob' 'figuratively' or 'rhetorically'. (d) Of two texts Allen says merely that he thinks Marx does not mean what he says: That the capitalist pumps 'booty' [Beute] out of the worker and that the capitalists divide among themselves the 'loot' [Beute] of other people's labor. 20 But why did Marx say 'Beute' if he did not mean it? Allen fails to explain this, or to give any other reason for accepting his forced reading. (e) Marx says that the surplus product is stolen (erwandt) without return of an equivalent from the English laborer. 21 Allen dismisses this statement, apparently on the ground that Marx here criticizes bourgeois apologists, and therefore could not mean 'erwandt' literally.22 This is a non sequitur. If anything, this context should imply that Marx did mean 'erwandt' literally. (f) In another passage (quoted at the start of this paper) Marx says that the capitalist only uses 'the old dodge of every conqueror who buys commodities from the conquered with the money he has robbed them of.'23 To minimize this text, Allen first says that because Marx thinks the 19 Allen, Appendix (2). 248. 20 Capital I, 596; Theories of Surplus Value (Moscow: 1968) II, 29. Allen's comment is at Allen, Appendix (4) and (5). 21 Capita/I,611. 22 Allen, Appendix (7), 249. 23 Capital I, 582. 258 Doing Marx Justice wage-exchange is just, he must speak 'figuratively' here of robbery.24 This ignores the crucial Marxian distinction between exchange and direct production, and between the worker as seller and as living com­ ponent of capital (see section I above). Second, and surprisingly, Allen also says that on Marx's view it is a mistake to view capitalist production as a relation between classes, and that because this text speaks in this mistaken way, it should not be taken literally.25 But as I explain below (section IV), Marx thought that on the contrary the only correct way to understand capitalist production was as a repeated transaction between the working class and the capitalist class. Wood thinks Marx could not have meant 'geraubten' literally in this text because the transactions Marx calls robbery (exacti ng tri bute, ex­ tracting surplus value) correspond to the dominant production relations and are therefore juSt. 26 As 1 explained in section I, however, Marx's 'correspondence' theory of justice applies only to exchange transac­ tions, and cannot apply to the extraction of surplus value. Moreover in this very text Marx takes pains to point out that robbery occurs despite the fact that equivalent is exchanged for equivalent in the market. Had Marx wishes to say what Wood and Allen ascribe to him, he would have said instead that because equivalents are exchanged in the market, there is no robbery outside the market. (g) In a passage 'I neglected in my earlier paper, Marx comments on Wagner's imputation to socialists of the view that profit on capital is 'only a deduction or 'theft' from the laborer': What a "deduction from the laborerll is, a deduction of his skin, etc., is not explained. Now in my presentation profit on capital is in fact also not "only a deduction or 'theft' from the laborer." On the contrary, I represent the capita­ list as a necessary functionary of capitalist production, and indicate at length that he does not only "deduct" or "rob" but enforces the production of surplus value and thus first helps to create what is to be deducted; I further indicate in detail that even if in commodity exchange only equivalents are exchanged, the capitalist - as soon as he has paid the laborer the real value of his labor power quite legally, i.e. by the law [Recht] corresponding to this mode of production, obtains surplus value. But all this does not rnake "profit on capital" into a "constitutive" element of value, but only proves that in the value, which is not "constituted" by the labor of the capitalist, something remains that he can "legally" appropriate, i.e. without violating the law corresponding to commo­ dityexchange. 27 24 Allen, Appendix (6), 248. 25 Ibid. 26 Wood [2], 278-9. "Lehrbuch der Dolitischen 6konomie",' Theoretical Practice I 5 (1972) 27 'Marginal Notes on Adolph 259 Gary Young Wood and Allen read this text in different ways. Wood takes it as an ex­ pression of the view that the extraction of surplus value is not robbery.28 But this ignores Marx's statement that the capitalist does not only rob the worker, which means that the capitalist at least robs the worker. Allen recognizes that Marx expressly says here that the capitalist steals surplus value from the worker, but concludes that Marx has misrepresented his own view!2 9 How could Marx have made such a clumsy mistake? Allen does not say_ Consider this text rnore closely. Wagner says that profit on capital is constituted by the activity of the capitalist in forming and deploying capital; it is not a theft from the worker. What does Marx reject in this position? Everything: Marx asserts that 0) profit is a theft or deduction from the worker, and is not constituted by the labor of the capitalist. But Marx adds that Oi) nonetheless the capitalist is not a parasite; he is a necessary functionary of capitalist production, the agent who forces the creation of surplus value by the worker. Therefore (iii) the capitalist has a right to surplus vaJue by the Recht corresponding to commodity exchange, even though that right does not arise from any value-creating labor of the capitalist. Marx had here a perfect opportunity to say that he agreed with Wagner that the extraction of surplus value is not theft. Instead, he said it is theft, but is also right according to the laws of commodity produc­ tion. This paradoxical assertion must be puzzling to anyone who, like Wood, Allen and Husami, assumes that 'theft' and 'right' cannot both be meant literally. But the passage makes good sense in light of the foregoing remarks. The capitalist's right to profit arises frorn the laws of commodity exchange, which are market rights, rights one has only in one's role as owner and buyer or seller. As a living component of capital, the worker has no market rights. But it is as living component of capital that the worker is exploited. When Marx says that capitalist exploitation is theft - and therefore unjust - he presupposes a background of rights that do not arise from one's status in the market. In sum, when Marx said that the extraction of surplus value from the worker was robbery by the capitalist, he meant 'robbery' in the ordinary sense in which robbery is unjust. The passages in Marx's writings sup­ porting this conclusion are too many and too clear to deny it. Moreover, Marx expressed similar views regarding the original institution of 28 Wood [2]/ 276-7. 29 AlienI 247 260 Doing Marx Justice capitalist class relations by the process he called 'primitive ac­ cumulation of capita!.' A brief review of Marx's description of the in­ justice of primitive accumulation will reinforce the conclusions we have already reached. III The original capital was formed by the advance of £10,000. How did the owner become possessed of it? "By his own labor and that of his forefathers," answer unanimously the spokesmen of Political Economy. And, in fact, their supposi­ tion appears the only one consonant with the laws of the production of commodities. 30 Having said this, Marx proceeds immediately to argue that the ad­ ditional £2,000 profit realized from the investment of this 'original capital' was obtained by robbery, though the capitalist has a right to it according to the laws of the production of commodities. 31 It is only later in Volume I of Capital that Marx returns to the 'original capital' and con­ tends that, from being the product of the labor of the capitalist and his forefathers, it too was acquired by systematic robbery. In its origin, as in its continuous reproduction, capitalist production rests upon theft. In this section J shall look at Marx's normative appraisal of primitive ac­ cumulation and its implications for our subject. Capitalist production requires the 'free' laborer - in a double sense of which Marx makes use in puns. The worker must be 'free' to sell his or her labor power, but must also be 'free' of ownership or control of the means of production, so he or she is cornpelled to sell labor power to the owner of the means of production, the capitalist. At the origin of capitalist production, in primitive accumulation, we therefore find the liberation of the workers-to-be: The immediate producer, the laborer, could dispose of his own person only after he had ceased to be attached to the soil and had ceased to be the slave, serf or bondsman of another. To become a free seller of labor-power, who carries his commodity wherever he finds a market, he must further have escaped from the of the guilds, their rules for apprentices and journey­ men, and the of their labor regulations. Hence the historical 30 Capital I, 582. 31 Ibid. 582-8. 261 Cary Young movement which changes the producers into wage-workers appears on the one hand as their emancipation from serfdom and from the fetters of the guilds, and this side alone exists for our bourgeois historians. But on the other hand these new freedmen became sellers of themselves only after they had been robbed [geraubt] of all their own means of production and of all the guarantees of existence afforded by the old feudal arrangements. And the history of this, their expropriation, is written in the annals of mankind in letters of blood and fire. 32 This robbery was carried out not only by means of private force, but by the Jaw, which in the eighteenth century became 'itself the instrurnent of the theft [des Raubs] of the people's land.'33 'The parliamentary form of the robbery [des Raubs] is that of Acts for enclosures of Commons, in other words, decrees by which the landlords grant themselves the people's land as private property, decrees of expropriation of the people.'34 And the objects of this robbery were four: The robbery [Raub] of the church's property, the fraudulent alienation [fraudu­ lente Verausserung] of the state domains, the theft [DiebstahIJ of the common lands, the usurpation of feudal and clan property and its transformation into modern private property under circumstances of reckless terrorism, were just so many idyllic methods of primitive accumulation. 35 In short, the working class was 'freed' by robbery. In making this statement Marx is manifestly not speaking of robbery rhetorically or figuratively. He is indignant; he is saying that it was unjust to do the act characterized as robbery. Marx's appraisal of primitive accumulation has two implications for our subject. First, Allen and Wood say that for Marx any concept of justice is a juridical concept, by which they at least mean that it is a con­ cept that is tied to a specific correlated sort of prod uction relations in two respects: one cannot intelligibly apply that concept of justice to other sorts of production relations or use it to criticize the correlated production relations. 36 But Marx's repeated characterization of primit­ ive accumulation as robbery shows that Wood and Allen are wrong. By definition, primitive accumulation took place during a trans­ 32 Ibid.715. 33 Ibid. 724. 34 Ibid. 35 Ibid. 732. See also pp. 714, 725,728. 36 Wood [1], 254-60; Allen, 222 262 Doing Marx Justice Ition period, in which no single set of production relations was dominant from beginning to end. Therefore no correlative juridical concepts apply throughout a transition period or warrant the con­ tinuous characterization of expropriation as robbery. On the view of Wood and Allen, it is inexplicable that Marx called primitive ac­ cumulation robbery. It is even more inexplicable that he said the rob­ bery was by Parliament and the law. 'Robbery' is here clearly not a 'juridical' concept. The second implication can be put in the form of a question: If primitive accumulation was robbery and hence unjust, how can the continued reproduction of capitalist relations, by means of the extrac­ tion of surplus value, be just? Does not the first theft taint all that follows? Perhaps not. But at the very least the first theft makes it much more difficult to maintain the justice of ongoing capitalist production, and this is a difficulty that neither Wood nor Allen has tried to over­ come. IV If the foregoing is correct, Marx regarded the wage-exchange as just to the worker as seller of labor power, and the extraction of surplus value as unjust to the worker as living component of capital. In my earlier paper I argued that Marx advanced the further thesis that the wage­ exchange is a mere appearance, that in reality capitalist production is simply the extraction of surplus value. Allen denies that Marx affirmed this non-reality thesis. Allen's premise is that Marx analyzed capitalist production by considering each act of exchange by itself, and not seeking relations between whole social c1asses.J7 But, as Allen correctly states, the non-reality thesis is correct (if at all) only when capitalist production is seen as a continuous transaction between working and capitalist classes. So, Allen concludes, Marx could not have adhered to the non-reality thesis. In support of his remarkable premise, Allen adduces a single text. Marx has just stated that the worker is paid the just price of his or her labor power. He goes on to say: 37 Allen, 234-7 263 Cary Young To be sure, the matter looks quite different if we consider capitalist produc­ tion in the uninterrupted flow of its renewal, and if, in place of the individual capitalist and the individual worker, we view them in their totality, the capita­ list class and the working class confronting each other. But in so doing we should be applying standards entirely foreign to commodity production. Only buyer and seller, mutually independent, face each other in commodity production. The relations between them cease on the day when the term sti­ pulated in the contract they concluded expires. If the transaction is repeated, it is repeated as the result of a new agreement which has nothing to do with the previous one and which only by chance brings the same seller together again with the same buyer. If, therefore, commodity production, or one of its associated processes, is to be judged according to its own economic laws, we must consider each act of exchange by itself, apart from any connexion with the act of exchange pre­ ceding it and that following it. And since sales and purchases are negotiated solely between particular individuals, it is not admissible to seek here for relations between whole social classes.'· Allen sees in this text an affirmation that the correct perspective from which to view capitalist production is that which ignores classes and class relations and treats individuals and their transactions atomistically: Marx intends ... to contrast two ways of regarding a wage transaction in which the wage is realized surplus value: one sees it as a relation between individuals, the other as a relation between classes. To regard it in the latter way is to apply standards foreign to commodity production. So, we seem warranted to infer, the correct way to regard it is as a relation between individuals. '9 But this inference is warranted only on the basis of a further premise: That (on Marx's view) capitalist production must be understood only in terms of standards that are not foreign to commodity production. This is a premise that Allen cannot find support for in Marx's writings. Allen brings this premise to the text himself. First, Marx regards most if not all bourgeois ideology as based on the reduction of capitalist production to mere commodity production, with a consequent emphasis upon market transactions and suppression of the specific nature of direct production, the locus of capitalist ex­ ploitation. This reduction 'contains the entire wisdom of the vulgar econom ists.' 40 Second, Marx's own analysis is expressly based on the view that capitalist production is the continuous repetition of a transaction, rather 38 Capital I, 586. 39 Allen, 235-6 40 'Results of the Immediate Process of Production: 1002. 264 Doing Marx Justice than a series of isolated exchanges, and moreover the repetition of a transaction that is unintelligible unless understood as taking place be­ tween two classes rather than between individuals who happen to be now buyers, now sellers in the market. This view pervades Marx's mature writings, but here I can only quote one striking illustration of it: The purchase of labour-power for a fixed period is the prelude to the pro­ cess of production; and this prelude is constantly repeated when the stipulated term comes to an end, when a definite period of production, such as a week or a month, has elapsed. But the labourer is not paid until after he has expended his labour-power, and realised in commodities not only its value, but surplus­ value. He has, therefore, produced not only surplus-value, which we for the present regard as a fund to meet the private consumption of the capitalist, but he has also produced, before it flows back to him in the shape of wages, the fund out of which he himself is paid, the variable capital; and his employment lasts only so long as he continues to reproduce this fund. Hence, that formula of the economists, referred to in Chapter XVIII., which represents wages as a share in the product itself. What flows back to the labourer in the shape of wages is a portion of the product that is continuously reproduced by him. The capitalist, it is true, pays him in money, but this money is merely the transmuted form of the product of his labour. While he is converting a portion of the means of production into products, a portion of his former product is being turned into money. It is his labour of last week, or of last year, that pays for his labour­ power this week or this year. The illusion begotten by the intervention of money vanishes immediately, if, instead of taking a single capitalist and a single labourer, we take the class of capitalists and the class of labourers as a whole. The capitalist class is constantly giving to the labouring class order-notes, in the form of money, on a portion of the commodities produced by the latter and appropriated by the former. The labourers give these order-notes back just as constantly to the capitalist class, and in this way get their share of their own product. The transaction is veiled by the commodity-form of the product and the money-form of the commodity41 Here it is precisely the invocation of a class perspective that is necessary to destroy the 'illusion' created by money and the commodity form. These texts make it amply clear that when Marx refers, in the passage upon which Allen relies, to 'standards entirely foreign to commodity production,' he is referring to the standards upon which his own analysis rests. Certainly it should be no surprise that Marx's analysis cannot be stated without essential reliance upon the interrelated con­ cepts of the working class, the capitalist class, and the transaction be­ tween them. Allen offers a second objection, apparently both to the non-reality thesis and to my claim that Marx asserted it. Allen says that 41 Capita/I, 567-8. See also the references in note 55 of 'Justice and Capital Pro­ duction.' 265 Gary Young it is obvious that the workers end up with means of consumption which they lacked when they entered their wage transactions, as Young recognizes. But this is enough to make the "total transaction" between labor and capital a genuine exchange. 42 It might be enough to make the total transaction a genuine or real ex­ change if the capitalist began the total transaction with the means of consumption and transferred them to the worker. But the means of con­ sumption are created by the worker during the transaction. The capitalist does not own them at the start, but only during a transitory in­ termediate phase of the total transaction. This passing ownership, as Marx says, 'disappears in the result' of the total transaction. That result is that, although the worker creates all value, a portion of that value (namely surplus value) is transferred to the capitalist. This transfer of surplus value is the essence of capitalist production, notwithstanding the fact that it is veiled and mystified by the rnarket transactions which mediate it. v Wood and Allen ascribe to Marx a view of justice that makes it unin­ telligible or otherwise impossible for Marx to employ justice as a critical concept, that to assert that the dominant production relations in a society are unjust. If Marx understood not only justice, but all value concepts, in this way, he would be precluded from criticizing capitalist production. Wood rightly rejects this absurd resu It. He attempts to escape it by denying that Marx understood freedom, self-actualization and other potentially critical concepts in the way understood justice. Of course Marx never describes freedom or self-actualization (as he does des­ cribe right and justice) as the correspondence of anything to prevailing produc­ tion relations. But this does not imply he is inconsistent. All it illlplies is that his conceptions of right and justice differ in this respect from his conceptions of freedom and self-actualization. 43 42 Allen, 234 43 Wood [2], 282. 266 Doing Marx Justice Thus on Wood's view, Marx sorts value concepts into two categories: Those like the concept of justice, which are merely 'juridical' concepts applicable only in an acritical way, and those like the concept of free­ dom, which are not at all 'juridical' concepts and may (must?) be used critically. In the foregoing sections I have argued that Marx's concept of justice (or at least one of Marx's concepts of justice) can be, and was by Marx, used critically, to assert that capitalist production is essentially and completely unjust. In conclusion I briefly note that Marx employed the concepts of freedom and self-development 'juridically' as well as critically. In other words, Marx sawall value concepts as having critical and acritical (ideological?) applications. (Or, if it is preferable to put it this way, he sawall value expressions as associated with two sorts of con­ cepts, critical and acritical.) In my earlier paper I discussed at length the concept of freedom associated with capitalist production and the manner in which (on Marx's view) it hides an underlying real slavery.44 A pointed anticipation of this distinction appears in the Communist Manifesto: By freedom is meant, under the present bourgeois conditions of productions, free trade, free selling and buying. But if buying and selling disappears, free selling and buying disappears also. This talk about free selling and buying, and all the other "brave words" of our bourgeoisie about freedom in general, have a meaning, if any, only in contrast with restricted buying and selling, with the fettered traders of the Middle Ages, but have no meaning when opposed to the communist abolition of buying and selling, of the bourgeois conditions of production, and the bourgeoisie itself. 45 This early statement is just as valid in the light of Marx's later work, ex­ cept that in his later work it became clearer that what must be abolished is not (merely?) buying and selling in general, but the buying and selling of labor power. As to self-actualization, a famous passage in the Crundrisse distinguishes three meanings or forms of self-actualization and relates each to a different set of production relations: pre-capitalist, capitalist and social ist. 46 In short, the ruling ideas of each age have ever been the ideas of its ruling c1ass,47 the ideas that legitimize the production relations that 44 'Justice and Capitalist Production,' 446-50. 45 'Communist Manifesto,' in Karl Marx: Political Writings, ed. David Fernbach (New York: 1973) 1,81-2. 46 Grundrisse, 487-8. 47 'Communist Manifesto,' 85. 267 Gary Young make it the ruling class. But the ruling ideas of an age do not exhaust the meaning or content of value expressions. It is possible to criticize a society using the same words its supporters invoke to defend it. 48 Are the of capitalist production 'free'? Nascent capitalists criticize their non-bourgeois societies as unfree because of restrictions on trade, in­ cluding trade in labor. Marx criticized capitalist production as unfree ­ and unjust - because of the forced extraction of surplus labor from the working class, which is made possible by the 'free' market in labor. Capitalist production both liberates and enslaves. It promotes and retards self-actualization. It is just and unjust. But (at least on Marx's view) the positive attributes of capitalist production all inhere in the market, and are absent from the sphere of direct production. It is as buyers and sellers that the agents of capitalist production are 'free,' can 'develop themselves' and are treated 'justly.' Turning from the market to direct capitalist production, however, we see that the working class is enslaved, retarded and robbed. And that, says Marx, is the essense and reality of capitalist production. 48 How this possible? 268 I II III IV v work_3irrwsvr6vcufk332kh4bk2txm ---- Does the Justice of the One Interact With the Justice of the Many? Reactions to Procedural Justice in Teams Jason A. Colquitt University of Florida This article reported the results of 2 studies that examined reactions to procedural justice in teams. Both studies predicted that individual members’ reactions would be driven not just by their own procedural justice levels but also by the justice experienced by other team members. Study 1 examined intact student teams, whereas Study 2 occurred in a laboratory setting. The results showed that individual members’ own justice interacted with others’ justice, such that higher levels of role performance occurred when justice was consistent within the team. These effects were strongest in highly interdependent teams and weakest for members who were benevolent with respect to equity sensitivity. Organizations continue to rely on teams as a means of structur- ing work (Devine, Clayton, Philips, Dunford, & Melner, 1999; Lawler, Mohrman, & Ledford, 1995). Teams act as a mechanism for pooling knowledge while placing decision-making authority in the hands of those closest to the work. They also provide a forum for between-person synergy, potentially improving creativity, in- novation, and adaptability. In addition, teams provide flexibility for many production tasks, as members can rotate and substitute for one another during the creation process. Indeed, some tasks require teams simply because of the total resources that must be allocated. From this perspective, team-based cooperation “justifies itself, then, as a means of overcoming the limitations restricting what individuals can do” (Barnard, 1938, p. 23). Teams can be defined as a collection of individuals who work together to complete some task, who share responsibility for col- lective outcomes, and who see themselves and are seen by others as a social entity (Cohen & Bailey, 1997; Guzzo & Dickson, 1996; Hackman, 1987; Sundstrom, DeMeuse, & Futrell, 1990). Teams can be differentiated from other kinds of work groups, such as departments or committees, by the depth and nature of their interdependence. By definition, teams possess two forms of struc- tural interdependence, defined by Wageman (2001) as features of the work context that define a relationship between entities built on mutual dependence. First, teams possess task interdependence— features of the work itself that require multiple individuals to cooperate to complete the work. Second, teams possess outcome interdependence—the degree to which shared rewards or conse- quences are contingent on collective (rather than individual) per- formance (Wageman, 2001). The increased use of teams has both practical and theoretical implications. From a practical perspective, organizations must take steps to ensure that employees are committed to their teams and that they perform their roles adequately. From a theoretical per- spective, scholars must consider the impact that team contexts have on the validity of findings derived from other settings. The team context offers an additional range of stimuli capable of altering members’ beliefs and reactions. In particular, team con- texts result in more intensive social comparisons among individual members because of the increased frequency and importance of team interactions. Consider the role of procedural justice in team contexts. Pro- cedural justice is defined as the fairness of decision-making pro- cesses (Leventhal, 1980; Thibaut & Walker, 1975). It is distinct from distributive justice, which is defined as the fairness of deci- sion outcomes (Adams, 1965; Leventhal, 1976). Past research has illustrated the benefits of procedural justice, which has been linked meta-analytically to a variety of reactions, including job perfor- mance (Colquitt, Conlon, Wesson, Porter, & Ng, 2001). Such results offer straightforward implications for managers: Experienc- ing just treatment can result in tangible improvements in employee reactions. However, a fundamental question relevant in team contexts remains unanswered: Does the justice experienced by other team members affect reactions as well? If so, it is not enough to treat individual members in a just manner—the other members must also enjoy such treatment. Unfortunately, past research has failed to differentiate the effects of individuals’ own justice and their assessment of others’ justice. It is important to understand the relative effects of own and others’ justice because treatment may vary within teams. Teams are becoming more diverse over time, An earlier version of this article was presented in Tom Tyler’s (Chair), Images of Justice in the Eyes of Employees: What Makes a Process Fair in Work Settings?, a symposium conducted at the 2000 meeting of the Academy of Management, Toronto, Ontario, Canada. This work was supported in part by Office of Naval Research Grant N00014 –93– 0983 and the Air Force Office of Scientific Research Grant F49620 –95– 0314 to Michigan State University (John Hollenbeck and Daniel Ilgen, principal investigators). This support does not imply agree- ment or disagreement by the supporting agencies of the ideas expressed herein. This article was based on my dissertation research, conducted at Mich- igan State University. I thank my advisor, John Hollenbeck, for his guid- ance and support. I also thank the other members of my dissertation committee—Donald Conlon, Raymond Noe, and Daniel Ilgen—for their valuable insights and suggestions. I thank Aleksander Ellis, Henry Moon, Bradley West, and Lori Sheppard for their assistance in data collection. Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to Jason A. Colquitt, Department of Management, Warrington College of Business Administration, University of Florida, P.O. Box 117165, Gainesville, FL 32611–7165. E-mail: colquitt@ufl.edu Journal of Applied Psychology Copyright 2004 by the American Psychological Association 2004, Vol. 89, No. 4, 633– 646 0021-9010/04/$12.00 DOI: 10.1037/0021-9010.89.4.633 633 with members possessing different functions, backgrounds, or demographic characteristics (Williams & O’Reilly, 1998). More- over, team leaders are often advised to dole out influence, support, and attention on a dyad-by-dyad basis (Gerstner & Day, 1997; Graen & Scandura, 1987). These factors increase the likelihood that own and others’ justice will differ, despite the fact that they possess two common causes (the team’s leader and the organiza- tion’s formal procedures). This article reports the results of two studies examining the effects of own and others’ justice on role performance in team contexts. The general proposition guiding this research was that the highest levels of role performance would be demonstrated when own and others’ justice were consistent within the team. Study 1 examined these effects in the context of ongoing student project teams, whereas Study 2 manipulated justice levels in a laboratory setting. Procedural Justice in Teams The procedural justice construct was introduced by Thibaut and Walker (1975) in their writings on conflict resolution procedures. Thibaut and Walker argued that procedural justice is fostered by allowing disputants to control the evidence presented during a procedure and by allowing them to influence the actual resolution decision. Specifically, they argued that “On the whole, distribution of control appears to be the best predictor of fairness and therefore of the preference for procedures” (p. 121). This control-based view has been one of the most popular conceptualizations of procedural justice for the past 2 decades (Colquitt et al., 2001) and has widespread applicability. For example, research has repeatedly shown that allowing employees to complete self-appraisals can enhance the perceived fairness of performance evaluation proce- dures (Gilliland & Langdon, 1998). Whereas Thibaut and Walker (1975) essentially equated proce- dural justice with control, Leventhal (1980) suggested that proce- dural justice can be fostered by adhering to six rules of fair treatment. Specifically, procedures should be (a) consistent across people and time, (b) based on accurate information, (c) unbiased, (d) correctable, (e) representative of all groups’ concerns, and (f) ethical. Leventhal’s rules also have widespread applicability. For example, employees view compensation systems as more fair when pay-raise decisions are performed consistently across people and are based on valid, accurate information (Miceli, 1993). The results of a recent meta-analysis of 183 studies conducted between 1975 and 2000 supported the relationship between control or rule-based criteria and procedural fairness perceptions (Colquitt et al., 2001). This review also linked procedural justice (whether operationalized in terms of control-based criteria, rule-based cri- teria, or fairness perceptions) to job satisfaction, organizational commitment, trust, citizenship behavior, and job performance. Although such outcomes would certainly seem valuable in team contexts, most of the studies included in the meta-analysis lacked the structural interdependence that defines teams. A handful of studies have begun to generalize these relation- ships to team contexts in which individuals possess both task and outcome interdependence. For example, Korsgaard, Schweiger, and Sapienza (1995) examined procedural justice in the context of laboratory decision-making teams. They linked control-based jus- tice to member attachment to the team, commitment to team decisions, and trust in the leader. Phillips and colleagues also examined the effects of procedural justice in laboratory teams (Phillips, 2002; Phillips, Douthitt, & Hyland, 2001). They linked control-based procedural justice to members’ satisfaction with the leader, attachment to the team, and efficacy perceptions. Finally, Colquitt and colleagues linked rule-based justice to member com- mitment and helping behavior, along with team performance and absenteeism (Colquitt, 2001; Colquitt, Noe, & Jackson, 2002). Although these studies have proven valuable in generalizing justice relationships to team contexts, they failed to consider a vital question: Does the justice experienced by others affect members’ own reactions? Five studies are relevant to this question, each of which relied on a control-based operationalization of procedural justice. Three of the studies followed a paradigm in which a participant was either given or denied some form of control over the experimental task, as was some unseen fictional other (Am- brose, Harland, & Kulik, 1991; Ambrose & Kulik, 1989; Grien- berger, Rutte, & van Knippenberg, 1997). Two of the studies failed to yield significant effects for others’ justice on reactions such as satisfaction and intentions to quit the activity (Ambrose et al., 1991; Ambrose & Kulik, 1989). The third study found a significant interaction between own and others’ justice such that the least favorable reactions occurred when own justice was low and others’ justice was high (Grienberger et al., 1997). Two studies by Lind, van den Bos, and colleagues have also examined the effects of own and others’ justice. In Lind, Kray, and Thompson’s (1998) study, 3 participants took part in a computer simulation in which they needed to make suggestions to a confed- erate supervisor. Own and others’ procedural justice were manip- ulated by responding to the suggestions with affirmative messages (granting control) or negative messages (denying control) and by allowing those responses to be viewed by all 3 participants. None of the manipulations affected performance on the task, and others’ justice had only weak effects on ratings of the supervisor. A follow-up study by van den Bos and Lind (2001) manipulated own and others’ justice using both control and rule-based operational- izations. Their results showed that participants’ affective reactions were higher when own and others’ justice were both high. These five studies provide only equivocal support for others’ justice affecting members’ own reactions. The predicted interac- tion has often been nonsignificant, and effects have never been observed for behavioral (as opposed to attitudinal) reactions. Those studies that have examined the Own � Others’ Justice interaction have used social comparisons as the theoretical mech- anism—a mechanism that has a long history in the justice litera- ture. Relative deprivation theory suggests that individuals react to subjective realities rather than objective realities by basing griev- ances on social comparisons (Crosby, 1984). Equity theory sug- gests that individuals do not react just to their own ratios of outcomes to contributions—they compare their personal ratios with those of some comparison other (Adams, 1965). These theories would predict that members would react more favorably when their own justice matches the levels experienced by others. It is interesting, however, that the social comparison mechanism has rarely been applied to procedural justice. Thibaut and Walker (1975) and Leventhal (1980) seemed to suggest that control-based and rule-based criteria are judged objectively, in absolute rather than relative terms. Indeed, Cropanzano and Am- brose (2001) noted, “In practice, this suggests that procedural 634 COLQUITT fairness is inferred relative to a theoretical standard, whereas distributive justice is inferred relative to a referent standard” (p. 136). Recent theorizing has begun to deemphasize this distinction. For example, referent cognitions theory was used to ground the pre- dictions of Ambrose et al. (1991) and Grienberger et al. (1997). The theory predicts that individuals consider referent outcomes— which compare the decision event with other easily imagined outcomes—when formulating their reactions (Folger, 1986, 1987). As the theory has evolved, Folger has acknowledged that referent outcomes can actually concern procedural phenomena, as when an individual imagines what would have happened if more control had been granted during a decision-making process (Folger, 1993). Fairness theory, a subsequent model derived from referent cog- nitions theory (Folger & Cropanzano, 1998, 2001), also acknowl- edges that social comparisons play a role when reacting to proce- dural information. Fairness theory restructures the referent cognitions mechanisms around the concept of counterfactual thinking—a process that forms mental representations of “what might have been.” These counterfactuals are built from several ingredients, including speculation, past experiences, norms, and social comparisons. Fairness theory’s counterfactuals ask whether an event could have played out differently, whether the authority should have behaved differently, and whether the member would have been better off if one of those alternatives had occurred instead. These questions are asked for both procedural issues and distributive issues. Thus fairness theory provides mechanisms that allow for social comparisons of procedural phenomena within teams. One should consider the example of a team working on a decision-making task. Past research has shown that control-based operationalizations of procedural justice are associated with mem- ber attachment to the team, commitment to team decisions, and trust in the team’s leader (Korsgaard et al., 1995; Phillips, 2002; Phillips et al., 2001). Now let one consider the reactions of an individual team member who is afforded little influence over the leader’s final decision. Will that member’s reactions depend on whether other members are granted similarly low levels (or mark- edly higher levels) of control? If social comparisons do occur for procedural phenomena, then an interactive effect of own and others’ justice should be observed. Figure 1 represents the predicted form of this interaction effect. The traditional main effect of a member’s own procedural justice is qualified by an interaction with others’ justice. When others’ justice is high, higher levels of own justice are associated with more beneficial reactions. However, when others’ justice is low, higher levels of own justice do not have beneficial effects. Taken together, the interaction is such that more beneficial effects occur when justice is consistent within the team. That is, outcomes are higher when members’ own justice levels match the levels of others’ justice (i.e., when both are high or both are low). This proposed effect forms the foundation for the two studies discussed in the remainder of this article. Study 1 Study 1 examined the effects of own and others’ justice in the context of student project teams. The interaction in Figure 1 was tested using member role performance as the dependent variable. Because past research on justice in team contexts has relied pri- marily on attitudinal outcomes, it remains unknown whether pro- cedural justice can alter the performance of team members. This is a critical question, because the success of the team often depends on the role performance of all members or even the weakest member (Steiner, 1972). Fortunately, procedural justice has been meta-analytically linked to performance, as Colquitt et al. (2001) found a corrected correlation of .36 between the two variables. Thus the following hypothesis was tested, consistent with Figure 1: Hypothesis 1: The positive relationship between own proce- dural justice and role performance will be moderated by others’ procedural justice, such that own role performance will be higher when justice is consistent within the team than when justice is not consistent within the team. Contextual and Individual Moderators It is important to note that Hypothesis 1 is advanced despite the inconsistent findings of past research. An important contribution of this article lies in the examination of potential moderators that could explain those inconsistencies and establish boundary condi- tions for the interaction effect. The choice of moderators was guided by the following question: What variables could enhance or neutralize the role of social comparisons within teams? Both studies included contextual and individual moderators to capture both sides of the person–situation distinction. Two specific mod- erators were examined in Study 1: task interdependence and collectivism. Task Interdependence As noted above, teams possess structural interdependence by definition in the form of task and outcome interdependence (Cohen & Bailey, 1997; Guzzo & Dickson, 1996; Hackman, 1987; Sund- strom et al., 1990). Of course, interdependence is not a dichotomous variable that teams either possess or lack. Wageman (2001) reviewed several conditions that can combine to make task interdependence levels more or less intense. In particular, task interdependence de- pends on the following four factors: (a) how the task is defined to the team, (b) what kinds of rules or instructions are given to the team, (c) the physical technology of the task, and (d) the degree to which necessary skills, resources, or abilities are spread among the group (Wageman, 2001). Thus, teams possess particularly high levels of interdependence when their task is defined in collective terms rather than by someFigure 1. Predicted pattern of Own � Others’ Procedural Justice interaction. 635REACTIONS TO PROCEDURAL JUSTICE division of labor, when rules or instructions require collective meetings or procedures, when the technology demands simulta- neous action, and when the inputs to the work are distributed such that everyone must contribute. It is important to note that Wage- man (2001) further argued that teams can take their structural interdependence and alter it through their actions. This point captures the distinction between structural interdependence and behavioral interdependence—the amount of task-related interac- tion actually engaged in (Wageman, 2001; see also Kiggundu, 1981). Teams with high structural interdependence may or may not exhibit high levels of behavioral interdependence and vice versa. Task interdependence should amplify the effect in Figure 1 by increasing the likelihood of social comparisons between a member and his or her teammates. Members working in highly interdepen- dent conditions must attend to and monitor their teammates to a greater degree (Kiggundu, 1981; Wageman, 2001). Thus task interdependence increases the visibility and salience of teammates’ treatment. It also increases discussion among members, which provides an opportunity for judging the justice received by others (Lind et al., 1998). Thus task interdependence should make it more likely that a member will notice when justice varies. Task interdependence should also foster a norm of equal treat- ment. Barrett-Howard and Tyler (1986) examined situations that make specific justice rules more or less important to justice judg- ments. Leventhal’s (1980) consistency rule was judged to be most important in task versus socially focused interaction, in formal versus informal interaction, and in cooperative versus competitive inter- action. This suggests that consistency with respect to justice should be especially critical under task-interdependent conditions, which are characterized by formal, cooperative, task-based interactions. Hypothesis 2: The benefits of consistency (in terms of the Own Procedural Justice � Others’ Procedural Justice inter- action in Hypothesis 1) for own role performance will be stronger when task interdependence is high than when task interdependence is low. Collectivism Collectivism can be defined as a social pattern in which indi- viduals see themselves as part of one or more collectives and are motivated by the norms, duties, and goals of those collectives (Triandis, 1995). The visibility of the construct was boosted by Hofstede’s (1980) study in which employees in a large multina- tional corporation answered questions about the importance of various work goals. Hofstede derived a collectivism factor from the survey and used the mean factor scores to create a national index of collectivism. A recent meta-analytic review revealed that between-culture differences in collectivism do exist but that the differences are smaller and less systematic than previously be- lieved (Oyserman, Coon, & Kemmelmeier, 2002). Triandis, Leung, Villareal, and Clack (1985) were among the first to examine collectivism at the individual level of analysis. They argued that allocentrism is a psychological variable that corresponds to the cultural version of collectivism. Allocentric individuals can be found in highly collective countries, such as Venezuela or Columbia, but can also be found in less collective countries, such as the United States or Australia. Subsequent research has dropped the allocentrism label in favor of collectiv- ism, though the term psychological collectivism is sometimes used to denote the individual-level version of the construct (e.g., Hui, Triandis, & Yee, 1991). Regardless of labeling, past research has conceptualized the construct using multiple dimensions (e.g., pref- erence for group work, concern for the group, willingness to sacrifice for the group; Earley, 1993; Triandis, Bontempo, Vil- lareal, Asai, & Lucca, 1988; Wagner, 1995) and has linked it to a variety of group-benefiting behaviors (Earley, 1989; Gibson, 1999; Moorman & Blakely, 1995). As with task interdependence, high levels of psychological collectivism should amplify the interaction effect in Figure 1 by increasing the likelihood of social comparisons between a member and his or her teammates. Gibson (1999) suggested that collective group members have an enhanced memory for team-relevant in- formation and a greater tendency to share such information with other members. Individuals who score high on collectivism also communicate more with in-group rather than out-group members and identify more with the collectives to which they belong (Tri- andis, 1995). Indeed, they are more likely to communicate using pronouns such as we rather than I (Triandis, 1995). Thus, collec- tive members should be more likely to notice when justice varies within the team. Past research also suggests that collective individuals value within-group consistency in treatment to a greater degree. Hui et al. (1991) showed that psychological collectivism is positively related to preferences for egalitarian rewards. Similarly, Ra- mamoorthy and Carroll (1998) showed that collective individuals are more accepting of alternative human resources practices such as equality in rewards. Finally, Waldman (1997) showed that members holding collective tendencies were more likely to prefer a group-based performance appraisal. On the basis of these results, I believed that collective members would be more likely to object to inconsistencies within the team. Hypothesis 3: The benefits of consistency (in terms of the Own � Others’ Procedural Justice interaction in Hypothesis 1) for own role performance will be stronger when members are high in collectivism than when members are low in collectivism. Method Participants Participants were 314 undergraduates (123 men and 191 women) en- rolled in an introductory management course at a large state university. All participants received course credit in exchange for their participation. Procedure The study was conducted in the context of five-person student project teams in an undergraduate management course. The teams were randomly composed at the beginning of the semester and worked together, both in and out of class, over the entire term. Teams worked on four exercises, each worth 10 points, and one semester-long project worth 80 points. The total available points in the class were 400, meaning that 30% of the students’ points were a function of their team’s work. This percentage created the kind of outcome interdependence that is considered a defini- tional part of being in a team (Cohen & Bailey, 1997; Guzzo & Dickson, 1996; Hackman, 1987; Sundstrom et al., 1990). 636 COLQUITT The four exercises covered the following content areas: selection, train- ing and development, performance management, and compensation. The exercises consisted of creating or improving one of these human resources systems, with the group turning in a single report summarizing and dis- cussing their views and opinions. These reports typically required at least 2 hr of work, much of it spent outside of class. The semester-long project required the teams to create an integrative paper that tied together all of the content domains of the course. The assignments created structural interdependence in two respects: (a) Outcome interdependence was created through a collective output with a collective (as opposed to individual) reward, and (b) task interdependence was created by defining the assignments as team (as opposed to individual) assignments. Still, behavioral interdependence varied across teams because instructions were not used to govern team processes, the physical technol- ogy (i.e., a computer) did not require collective action, and the distribution of relevant skills and abilities varied across teams. Thus, some teams completed the bulk of their work in combined face-to-face meetings whereas other teams split up the assignment and worked more independently. The justice, task interdependence, and collectivism measures were ad- ministered as part of a survey given to students in class. Students were assured that their instructor would receive only aggregated feedback re- garding the survey once the semester was complete. The procedural justice items referenced the grading procedures used to decide assignment grades. The timing of the survey was 1 week prior to the final exam, just after the teams had been given the last of their project grades. Thus, all team points had been allocated, and the majority of the overall course’s points had been allocated as well (the final exam was 25% of the grade). Given that the instructors were the ones computing the grades, the procedural justice items also referenced the instructors as the enactors of the procedures. Measures All measures used a 5-point scale ranging from 1 (strongly disagree) to 5 (strongly agree). Role performance. Performance was measured by five-item peer as- sessments that were completed at home and turned in just before the final exam. The instructors used the measure to gauge contributions to the project. Each member was rated by all 4 of his or her teammates, and members did not rate themselves. Two items assessed beneficial behaviors: “This member did his/her fair share of the work” and “This member was valuable to the group.” The other three items assessed negative behaviors and were reverse scored: “This member let other group members do most of the work,” “This member did not cooperate well with the group,” and “This member was not valuable to the group.” Interrater reliability for the five peer-rated items was assessed using the single-measure form of the intraclass correlation (ICC(1); James, 1982; Shrout & Fleiss, 1979). Each of the k ratees assumed the role of a treatment in a one-way analysis of variance (ANOVA), with raters (who were nested under the ratees) providing scores on the five items. The magnitude of the ICC(1) can be interpreted as the reliability associated with a single assess- ment of the ratee’s performance, with high values being in the .30 area (Bliese, 2000). The ICC(1)s for the role performance items were all high: .39 for Item 1, .30 for Item 2, .38 for Item 3, .44 for Item 4, and .40 for Item 5. Within-group agreement was assessed using the rwg index created by James, Demaree, and Wolf (1984; see also Lindell, Brandt, & Whitney, 1999). Unlike ICC(1), rwg considers only within-rater variance by com- paring agreement among raters with what would be expected from random ratings. The rwg(j) allows for the examination of within-group agreement at the scale (as opposed to the item) level, with aggregation usually supported by a mean rwg(j) above .70. The role performance scale had an rwg(j) of .91, again supporting aggregation across raters. The scale had a coefficient alpha of .93. Own procedural justice. Procedural justice was operationalized using what Lind and Tyler (1988) termed a direct measure. Specifically, mem- bers’ own procedural justice was assessed with the following two items (� � .73): “The grading procedures which decide my own individual grades have been fair” and “My instructor has treated me fairly.” Others’ procedural justice. Others’ procedural justice was assessed with two similar items (� � .78): “The grading procedures which decide my teammates’ grades have been fair” and “My instructor has treated my teammates fairly.” Task interdependence. Task interdependence was measured using the following two items taken from Johnson, Johnson, Buckman, and Richards (1988; � � .75): “When we worked together in our group, we could not complete the exercise unless everyone contributed” and “When we worked together in our group, everyone’s ideas were needed if we were going to be successful.” Collectivism. Collectivism was measured using three items taken from Wagner (1995; � � .68): “I prefer to work with others in a group rather than working alone,” “Given the choice, I’d rather do a job where I can work alone, rather than doing a job where I have to work with others in a group,” (reverse scored) and “Working with a group is better than working alone.” The collectivism literature has been plagued by measurement problems, and a recent review pointed to the good psychometric properties of this measure (Earley & Gibson, 1998). However, it is important to note that this measure captures only one dimension of a multidimensional construct. Control variables. Perceptions of distributive fairness were gathered as a control variable to avoid potential unmeasured variable problems. Four ad hoc items were used (� � .93), including “How justified is your grade given your performance in this class?” and “How much do you agree with your grade, given what you have contributed to the class?” (items were measured using a 5-point scale ranging from 1 � not at all to 5 � very much). Results and Discussion The means, standard deviations, and correlations for all vari- ables are shown in Table 1. The study’s hypotheses were tested using moderated regression, with the results shown in Table 2. In the first step of the regression, I controlled for the effects of distributive fairness. In the second step, I tested the direct effects of own and others’ procedural justice, and neither effect was significant. The test of Hypothesis 1 occurred in Step 3, in which I entered the Own � Others’ Procedural Justice interaction. The interaction had a significant effect on role performance. The plot of the interaction effect closely resembles Figure 1. High levels of own procedural justice had more positive effects when others were also afforded high levels (i.e., when justice was consistent within the team), supporting Hypothesis 1. In Step 4 of the regression I examined the main effects of the two moderators, and neither had significant effects. In Step 5 I entered all possible two-way interactions, which had to be entered before examining the three-way interactions used to test Hypoth- eses 2 and 3. The set of two-way interactions had a significant effect, driven by the interaction of others’ procedural justice with task interdependence and collectivism. Although not the subject of any hypotheses, these interactions indicated that others’ justice had stronger effects on role performance when task interdependence or collectivism was high. Finally, in Step 6 I entered the three-way interactions. As a set, the interactions had a significant effect, driven by the three-way interaction of own procedural justice, others’ procedural justice, and task interdependence. The plot of this interaction is shown in Figure 2. Differences in own and others’ procedural justice had much stronger effects on role performance when task interdepen- 637REACTIONS TO PROCEDURAL JUSTICE dence was high, supporting Hypothesis 2. The three-way interac- tion with collectivism was not significant, failing to support Hy- pothesis 3. Study 2 Although the results of Study 1 were supportive, some limita- tions should be noted. First, a correlational design was used, making it impossible to say that the interaction of own and others’ justice caused variation in role performance. Second, procedural justice was assessed globally, making it difficult to compare the results of Study 1 with past research, most of which has relied on control-based operationalizations (e.g., Ambrose et al., 1991; Grienberger et al., 1997; Lind et al., 1998). Third, the measure of role performance was a peer report focusing on contributions, as opposed to an objective bottom-line outcome. Finally, only one type of reaction was examined. Although member role perfor- mance is undoubtedly important, it is necessary to consider other types of reactions. Study 2 addressed each of these limitations. An experimental design was utilized to manipulate both own and others’ procedural justice using the control-based operationalization used in past research. Moreover, multiple outcomes were examined, including procedural fairness perceptions, cooperation, conflict, and an ob- jective measure of role performance. The same general prediction as in Study 1 was tested in Study 2, that the main effect of members’ own justice would be qualified by an interaction with others’ justice. Hypothesis 4: The positive effect of own procedural justice on fairness perceptions, cooperation, conflict, and role perfor- mance will be moderated by others’ procedural justice, such that more favorable reactions will occur when justice is consistent within the team than when justice is not consistent within the team. Contextual and Individual Moderators Although the interaction of own and others’ justice received support in Study 1, one should remember that past research remains inconsistent in its findings. Thus moderators of this effect were again examined. As in Study 1, the moderators focused on variables that should increase the likelihood of Table 1 Descriptive Statistics and Zero-Order Correlations for Study 1 Variable M SD 1 2 3 4 5 6 Justice variables 1. Own justice 4.10 0.74 — 2. Others’ justice 4.07 0.80 .69* — Moderators 3. Task interdependence 2.95 1.00 .08 .03 — 4. Collectivism 2.93 0.67 �.07 �.03 .15* — Outcome variable 5. Role performance 4.55 0.46 .10* .08 �.03 �.02 — Control variable 6. Distributive fairness 3.69 0.94 .50* .33* .01 .01 .10* — Note. N � 282 after listwise deletion. * p � .05, one-tailed. Table 2 Moderated Regression Results for Study 1 Regression step Role performance R2 �R2 � 1. Distributive fairness .01 .01 0.10 2. Own justice .01 .00 0.06 Others’ justice 0.02 3. Own Justice � Others’ Justice .03* .02* 0.60* 4. Task interdependence .03 .00 �0.03 Collectivism �0.00 5. Own Justice � Task Interdependence .09* .06* �0.31 Others’ Justice � Task Interdependence �0.98* Own Justice � Collectivism 0.33 Others’ Justice � Collectivism 1.24* 6. Own Justice � Others’ Justice � Task Interdependence .11* .02* 2.69* Own Justice � Others’ Justice � Collectivism 0.08 Note. N � 282 after listwise deletion. * p � .05. 638 COLQUITT social comparisons within teams. The contextual moderator was again task interdependence, and the individual moderator was equity sensitivity. Task Interdependence Study 2 attempted to replicate the effect shown in Figure 2, in which task interdependence amplified the effects of differences in own and others’ justice. I hypothesized that task interdependence should increase the likelihood of social comparisons within the teams by increasing the attention devoted to other members (Kig- gundu, 1981; Wageman, 2001) while fostering a norm of equal treatment (Barrett-Howard & Tyler, 1986). Hypothesis 5: The benefits of consistency (in terms of the Own � Others’ Procedural Justice interaction in Hypothesis 4) for fairness perceptions, cooperation, conflict, and role performance will be stronger when task interdependence is high than when task interdependence is low. Equity Sensitivity Equity sensitivity is a stable characteristic that assesses one’s preferences for and sensitivity to various equity levels (Huseman, Hatfield, & Miles, 1987; King, Miles, & Day, 1993; Miles, Hat- field, & Huseman, 1989). Equity sensitivity can be conceptualized using two ends of a continuum. At one end is the benevolent pattern, characterized by a tolerance for situations in which ratios of inputs to outcomes do not match those of a comparison other (Huseman et al., 1987). Individuals high in benevolence are more focused on ensuring that their inputs are adequate and do not attend to outcomes as much as other individuals (King et al., 1993). At the other end is the entitled pattern, characterized by an intolerance of underreward situations. Individuals near this end of the equity sensitivity continuum are more focused on the receipt of outcomes and are less forgiving of any outcome inconsistencies (King et al., 1993). Similar to collectivism, equity sensitivity is an individual dif- ference that should affect the likelihood of social comparisons between a member and his or her teammates. Huseman et al. (1987) initially suggested that benevolents are “givers,” whose happiness is maximized when they are underrewarded relative to peers and minimized when they are overrewarded relative to peers (p. 225). This matches the lay definition of benevolence and is also congruent with the use of the term in the trust literature (Mayer, Davis, & Schoorman, 1995). However, subsequent research sug- gests that this conceptualization is too limited. King et al. (1993) showed that benevolent individuals reported higher levels of sat- isfaction than did entitled individuals in both overreward and underreward inequity conditions. King et al.’s (1993) findings suggest that benevolent individuals either engage in fewer social comparisons or are less affected by the social comparisons that they do make. Given the implications of equity sensitivity for reactions to under- or overreward circum- stances, it seems logical that equity sensitivity could alter reactions to differences in procedural justice. However, equity sensitivity has been used only in relation to outcome distributions and never in relation to procedural variables. Thus in the current study I attempted to generalize King et al.’s findings to procedural differences in teams. Hypothesis 6: The benefits of consistency (in terms of the Own � Teammates’ Procedural Justice interaction in Hy- pothesis 1) for fairness perceptions, cooperation, conflict, and role performance will be weaker for more benevolent mem- bers than for more entitled members. Method Participants Participants were 300 undergraduates (164 men and 136 women) en- rolled in an introductory management course at a large state university. Participants signed up for time slots during the first day of the course, with slots limited to eight people. They waited in a lobby on arriving at the laboratory, and teams were randomly formed from the participants present. Two experimental sessions could be run at one time, and any additional participants took part in an overflow study. All participants received course credit in exchange for their participation and were given a chance to earn a small cash incentive ($10) based on their team’s performance. This incentive was given to the participants in the top three teams within each of the experimental conditions (around 18% of the teams). The use of the incentive encouraged a baseline level of motivation and psychological engagement on the part of the participants. Task Participants worked on a special version of the Team Interactive Deci- sion Exercise for Teams Incorporating Distributed Expertise (TIDE2) com- puter simulation. An extensive description of this task is given in Hollen- beck et al.’s study (1995). Four participants, termed Alpha, Bravo, Charlie, and Delta, served as a team and were stationed at networked computer terminals. Participants were required to classify aircraft as friendly or threatening on the basis of nine pieces of aircraft information (size, speed, range, altitude, direction, angle, radar type, frequency, direction, and cor- ridor position). It was explained that this task was modeled after the one performed by Air Force command and control teams. Bravo, Charlie, and Delta (who were referred to as staff members) provided classification recommendations to the team leader, Alpha. Alpha was actually one of the experimenters serving as a confederate. Bravo, Charlie, and Delta were each responsible for gathering four of the nine pieces of aircraft information, and they were given extensive training on how to transform information values into probable threat levels. For example, Bravo was responsible for gathering size, speed, radar type, and frequency information and was trained on what types of values were Figure 2. Own � Others’ Justice � Interdependence interaction for performance (Study 1). 639REACTIONS TO PROCEDURAL JUSTICE threatening (e.g., smaller aircraft were more threatening). Participants gathered some of their information by using their Measure menu, which instantly provided information values to them. However, participants could measure only a subset of their assigned information, and they depended on their teammates to provide them with the remainder. For example, Bravo could measure size, range, direction, and corridor position but was in charge of interpreting only size. Bravo relied on Charlie and Delta to provide information on Bravo’s other assigned information (speed, radar type, and frequency) by sending that information through the network. In turn, Bravo provided Charlie and Delta with the range, direction, and corridor position information they required. Team members were explicitly instructed that all pieces of information were equally important (i.e., speed information was not any more useful than was radar type information) and were informed that Alpha was so instructed as well. This instruction was given to prevent participants from attributing their levels of control to the set of information they gathered. Team members were also told that Alpha could measure all nine pieces of information independently but was given only very general training on how to interpret the values. They were also told not to request information from Alpha, because he or she had to fulfill other duties as team leader and may not have time to respond to them. In addition, all team members could type text messages to one another through the computer network. Messages from Alpha were sent to all 3 staff members simultaneously and were visible to all team members. Once Bravo, Charlie, and Delta had studied the four pieces of information they were in charge of interpreting, they made recommendations to Alpha in terms of a probable aircraft threat level. Their recommendations took the form of a course of action on a 7-point continuum of aggressiveness (1 � ignore, 2 � review, 3 � monitor, 4 � warn, 5 � ready, 6 � lock-on, and 7 � defend). For example, if Bravo’s size and speed information were moder- ately threatening and the frequency and radar type information were very threatening, he or she would likely recommend a ready or a lock-on to Alpha. Once Bravo, Charlie, and Delta had each made his or her recom- mendation, Alpha combined those recommendations to form one final team decision. This combination was performed using a script that manipulated the extent to which specific members’ recommendations were considered. Once Alpha registered the final decision, that decision was compared with the correct one. Teams were given feedback via the computer on the absolute difference between the team’s final decision and the correct decision. No difference was termed a hit, a 1-point difference was a near miss, a 2-point difference was a miss, a 3-point difference was an incident, and a 4-point or more difference was a disaster. This same process was then repeated for 36 trials, including 3 practice trials. Trials alternated between 150 s and 120 s in length. In addition to the decision-accuracy feedback, team members were given bogus feedback on the correlation between their recommendation and Alpha’s final decision over the course of the trials. This feedback took the form of a green bar that used a scale ranging from 0 (no correlation) to 1 (a perfect correlation). This form of feedback has been used in past research using TIDE2 (Hollenbeck, Ilgen, LePine, Colquitt, & Hedlund, 1998; Phillips, 2002). In the current study, the green bars were scripted to achieve specific levels depending on the experimental condition, and each member’s bar was viewable by the entire team. Manipulations The manipulations formed a 2 (own procedural justice: high or low) � 2 (others’ procedural justice: high or low) � 2 (task interdependence: high or low) design. Own procedural justice. Own procedural justice was manipulated by providing members with varying levels of control over the team’s final decisions. The manipulation assumed three forms. First, the script used by the confederate to combine Bravo’s, Charlie’s, and Delta’s recommenda- tions into one overall decision weighed members’ recommendations as 1.63 in the high condition and 0.38 in the low condition.1 Whereas participants could, to some extent, naturally perceive how much they were being weighed by the leader, the manipulation also provided feedback on the size of those weights via the green bars mentioned above. In the high condition, the bars centered around an 8-cm length, whereas in the low condition the bars centered around a 2-cm length. Third, the manipulation used text messages transmitted from the confederate to Bravo, Charlie, and Delta indicating the presence of control, similar to the justice manipulation used by Lind et al. (1998). Sample messages were “BRAVO: I leaned toward your call on that one” and “CHARLIE: I leaned toward your input there.” In designing the messages, great care was taken to ensure that the messages sounded neutral rather than overly respectful and did not explain the reasons behind the presence of control, ensuring that the procedural justice manipulation was not confounded with interactional justice (Bies & Moag, 1986). In the high condition the participants received six text messages (three between Trials 10 and 19 and three between Trials 20 –36), whereas in the low condition the participants received zero messages.2 Others’ procedural justice. Others’ procedural justice was manipu- lated by varying the levels of control given to a member’s teammates. Control was manipulated in the same three forms: the weights that Alpha used to combine members’ recommendations, the green bars assigned to members’ stations, and the text messages sent to the members. As in Lind et al.’s (1998) study, participants could read messages sent to them by Alpha and could also read messages sent to their teammates by Alpha. It was explained that this type of monitorable communication is used by real Air Force teams. The same levels were used to create the following high and low levels of justice: 1.63 versus 0.38 weights, 8- versus 2-cm green bars, and six versus zero text messages. Twenty 3-person teams were run under the uniformly high control condition. The 60 participants in these teams were in the high own justice– high others’ justice condition. Twenty 3-person teams were run under the uniformly low control condition. The 60 participants in these teams were in the low own justice–low others’ justice condition. Sixty 3-person teams were run under the varying control condition. Sixty of these 180 team members received more control than did either of their team- mates and were in the high own justice–low others’ justice condition. Sixty of these 180 team members received less control than did either of their teammates and were in the low own justice– high others’ justice condition. The remaining 60 participants received more control than did one of their team- mates but less control than did the other (with weights of 1.00, green bars of 5 cm, and three messages). These 60 participants were therefore omitted from the 2 � 2 design. Thus all analyses were based on N � 240 participants.3 1 The relative magnitudes of these recommendation weights were scaled to be 1 standard deviation higher and 1 standard deviation lower than the average weights from past studies using the TIDE2 simulation (Hollenbeck, Colquitt et al., 1998; Hollenbeck, Ilgen et al., 1998). 2 These frequencies were also based on past research using the TIDE2 simulation (Hollenbeck, Colquitt et al., 1998; Hollenbeck, Ilgen et al., 1998). 3 These “in-between” participants received intermediate levels of con- trol. Their recommendations were weighed 1.00 by Alpha, their green bars were 5 cm in length, and they received three text messages. Exploratory analyses revealed that the 60 in-between participants did not differ from the remaining 240 participants on any of the four dependent variables. Thus there was no effect for being “in between” versus not “in between.” However, these participants did feel significantly more fairly treated than did the low own control– high teammates’ control participants, t(298) � 4.34; M � 3.49 versus 3.06; p � .01, and they felt significantly less fairly treated than did the high own control– high teammates’ control partici- pants, t(298) � –2.42; M � 3.49 versus 3.73; p � .05. The in-between participants also felt less conflict than did the low own control–low teammates’ control participants, t(298) � –2.19; M � 1.99 versus 2.20; p � .05, and the low own control– high teammates’ control participants, t(298) � �1.90; M � 1.99 versus 2.17; p � .06. 640 COLQUITT Task interdependence. Task interdependence was manipulated by varying the degree to which members depended on their teammates in gathering their assigned information. In high task-interdependence condi- tions, team members could measure only one of the four pieces of infor- mation they were in charge of gathering. This meant that they relied on their teammates to send them the other three pieces of information. One of those pieces of information could be delivered by either teammate and the other two could be delivered only by one specific teammate. In low task-interdependence conditions, team members could measure three of the four pieces of information they were in charge of gathering, meaning that they relied on their teammates for only one piece of information. That piece came from one specific teammate. In Wageman’s (2001) terms, the ma- nipulation affects structural task interdependence by altering the distribu- tion of resources and information among individuals. Procedure Four participants were brought into one of the computer rooms where they filled out a consent form. One of the participants was then led from that room to another room, ostensibly to fill the role of Alpha. It was explained that Alpha would be separated from the other 3 team members because actual Air Force teams are characterized by geographic separation. In reality, this person then took part in a separate research study. The three remaining participants then received a booklet that provided an overview of the decision-making task. After reading the booklets for 10 min, the participants were given 45 min of training consisting of three practice trials. Participants next completed a survey including the measure of equity sensitivity. The simulation then began with Trial 4, at which point the experimenter left the room and assumed the role of Alpha (previously filled by another member of the research laboratory’s staff). During these initial trials, the green bars gradually drifted toward their manipulated level, arriving there on Trial 10. On Trial 9, Alpha sent all participants a text message asking them to input their recommendations in a timely manner (“ALL: I need about 20 –30 seconds to look at everything”). The halfway point of the experiment was reached on Trial 19, after which there was a short inter- mission to fill out a survey that included the justice condition manipulation check items and the measure of fairness perceptions. Participants then completed the remaining trials (Trials 20 –36). After the final trial they were given a final survey, which included the measure of conflict. Partic- ipants were then given a general debriefing, which was supplemented by a full debriefing at the conclusion of the semester. Measures Procedural fairness. Procedural fairness perceptions were assessed with five items (� � .71). Samples included “The procedure Alpha has used to make the final team decision has been fair to me,” “The way Alpha has made the final team decision has been fair to me,” and “The procedure Alpha has used in making the final team decision has been free of bias.” (1 � strongly disagree to 5 � strongly agree). Conflict. The seven-item measure used by Saavedra, Earley, and Van Dyne (1993) was used to assess conflict (� � .79). Samples included “I found myself unhappy and in conflict with members of my group,” “I found myself in conflict with other group members because of their actions (or lack of actions),” and “There was a lot of tension between myself and others in the group.” (1 � strongly disagree to 5 � strongly agree). Cooperation. Cooperation was assessed using preexisting indices in TIDE2. The simulation tracks when members ask for information from a teammate, when that teammate receives that request, when that teammate responds to that request, and when the member receives the requested information. From this information, TIDE2 outputs the following indices: slights (failing to read an information request), unresponsives (reading an information request but not acting on it), lectures (sending information without a request), and learns (sending information in response to a request). Cooperation by an individual team member was operationalized as the number of times a member performed lectures and learns minus the number of times a member performed slights and unresponsives, averaged across Trials 10 –36. Because I was treating multiple trials as multiple items, cooperation had an alpha of .95. Role performance. Role performance was operationalized using decision-making accuracy. The specific accuracy index was mean-squared error, the square of the difference between what the participant should have recommended to Alpha (on the basis of the four pieces of information they were in charge of) and what the participants actually did recommend, aggregated across Trials 10 –36. Gigone and Hastie (1997) argued that mean-squared error is a superior measure of decision-making accuracy because it gives more weight to extreme errors, does not ignore the absolute differences between decisions and true scores (unlike correlation- based measures), and can be decomposed into more specific, complemen- tary accuracy facets (see Hollenbeck, Colquitt, Ilgen, LePine, & Hedlund, 1998). In the current study, mean-squared error was given a negative sign so that higher (i.e., less negative) values represented higher levels of accuracy. Because I was treating multiple trials as multiple items, the mean-squared error had an � � .71. It is important to note that this measure is conceptually different than that used in Study 1. This measure focuses less on member behaviors and more on the bottom-line outcome of mem- bers’ behaviors (i.e., whether the recommendation was accurate). Equity sensitivity. Equity sensitivity was assessed using the measure validated in King and Miles’s (1994; � � .75) study. The instructions read “The questions below ask what you’d like for your relationship to be with any organization for which you might work. On each question, divide 10 points between the two choices (choice A and choice B) by giving the most points to the choice that is most like you and the fewest points to the choice that is least like you. You can, if you’d like, give the same number of points to both choices. And you can use zeros if you like.” One item read, “I would be more concerned about: (A) What I received from the organiza- tion; (B) What I contributed to the organization.” Another item read, “It would be more important for me to: (A) Get from the organization; (B) Give to the organization.” Scores were created by summing the number of points allocated to Option B for the five items. Thus higher scores repre- sented higher levels of benevolence. Control variables. As in Study 1, perceptions of distributive fairness were assessed as a control variable. The outcome was the team’s score at the conclusion of the simulation, which was affected by the leader’s behavior and decided the team’s eligibility for the cash incentive. Partic- ipants were asked to judge how fair the score was using three items with the following anchors: 1 (it was unfair) to 5 (it was fair), 1 (it was unjust) to 5 (it was just), and 1 (it was unsatisfactory) to 5 (it was satisfactory; these three items had an alpha of � .81). Results and Discussion Manipulation Checks The manipulation check of own control was assessed with the following item: “My recommendations have influenced Alpha’s final decision” (1 � strongly disagree to 5 � strongly agree). An ANOVA yielded the anticipated main effect for own control, F(1, 238) � 64.97, p � .01; Mhigh � 3.44, Mlow � 2.58, � 2 � 0.22. The manipulation check of others’ control was assessed with the fol- lowing item: “My teammates have had a lot of influence over Alpha’s final decision” (1 � strongly disagree to 5 � strongly agree). An ANOVA also yielded the anticipated main effect for others’ control, F(1, 238) � 48.25, p � .01; Mhigh � 3.72, Mlow � 3.05; �2 � 0.17. The manipulation check of task interdependence 641REACTIONS TO PROCEDURAL JUSTICE was assessed by measuring how often participants asked their teammates for information, on average, per trial. An ANOVA yielded the anticipated main effect for task interdependence, F(1, 238) � 157.56, p � .01; Mhigh � 1.79, Mlow � .37, � 2 � 0.40. Tests of Hypotheses The means, standard deviations, and correlations are shown in Table 3, and the regression results are shown in Table 4. In step Step 1 I controlled for the effects of distributive fairness, which was significantly related to three of the outcomes. In Step 2 I examined the direct effects of own and others’ justice. Own justice had a positive effect on fairness perceptions and a negative effect on conflict. In Step 3 I entered the Own � Others’ Justice inter- action used to test Hypothesis 4. The interaction had a significant effect on fairness perceptions, cooperation, and decision-making accuracy but not conflict. Each plot resembled the pattern in Figure 1, supporting Hypothesis 4. In Step 4 I examined the main effects of the two moderators, with neither having significant effects. In Step 5 I entered all possible two-way interactions, which had to be controlled before examining the three-way interactions. Finally, Step 6 entered the three-way interactions, with significant results observed for con- flict, cooperation, and decision-making accuracy using task inter- dependence and fairness perceptions and for conflict using equity sensitivity. Sample plots are shown in Figures 3 and 4. Differences between own and others’ justice had stronger effects when task interdependence was high and weaker effects when members were more benevolent. These results offer support for Hypotheses 5 and 6. General Discussion As noted at the outset, the increased use of teams has both practical and theoretical implications. From a practical perspec- tive, scholars must examine methods of improving performance in team contexts. From a theoretical perspective, scholars must ex- amine the impact of the team context on the validity of findings derived from less interdependent contexts. With that in mind, the two studies reported here examined procedural justice in teams. The results of the two studies suggest that treating members in a just manner does have some practical benefit. Members’ own procedural justice levels were positively related to their role per- formance (in Study 1) and to their conflict perceptions (in Study 2). This adds to the handful of existing studies on procedural justice in teams, which have linked members’ justice to attachment to the team, commitment to team decisions, leader evaluations, and helping (Colquitt, 2001; Colquitt et al., 2002; Korsgaard et al., 1995; Phillips, 2002; Phillips et al., 2001). However, what stands out most from these results is the impor- tance of considering the impact of others’ procedural justice. Members seemed to use the social comparisons made possible by team contexts when reacting to justice levels. As a result, the traditional main effect of members’ own justice was qualified by an interaction in which more positive reactions occurred when treatment was consistent within the team. Indeed, this interaction explained 8 times more variance in members’ cooperation and performance than did the own justice main effect. Past research has been inconclusive about the importance of own versus others’ procedural justice comparisons (Ambrose et al., 1991; Ambrose & Kulik, 1989; Grienberger et al., 1997; Lind et al., 1998; van den Bos & Lind, 2001). However, the previous studies did not use true team contexts, as the “other” was fre- quently fictional, never to be seen by the participants. The two studies reported here placed participants in true teams, marked by the interdependence, common fate, and collective identity that have come to define the team label (Cohen & Bailey, 1997; Guzzo & Dickson, 1996; Hackman, 1987; Sundstrom et al., 1990). The interaction of own and others’ justice was demonstrated for a variety of outcomes, including role performance (Studies 1 and 2), procedural fairness perceptions (Study 2), and cooperation (Study 2). More important, both studies illustrated the boundary conditions for the interaction. Specifically, the interaction tended to be stronger as task interdependence became higher, an effect that was significant in four of five tests. The interaction tended to be weaker when members were more benevolent in terms of equity sensitivity, though that effect was significant in only two of four tests. Less support was shown for the moderating role of collec- Table 3 Descriptive Statistics and Zero-Order Correlations for Study 2 Variable M SD 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 Justice manipulations 1. Own justice 1.50 0.50 — 2. Others’ justice 1.50 0.50 .00 — Moderators 3. Task interdependence 1.50 0.50 .00 .00 — 4. Equity sensitivity 27.12 5.46 �.06 .09 �.02 — Outcome Variables 5. Fairness perceptions 3.44 0.56 .29* �.06 �.10 .03 — 6. Conflict 2.11 0.59 �.20* �.08 .01 �.13* �.40* — 7. Cooperation 0.15 3.70 �.06 .03 �.05 �.04 .10 �.15* — 8. Decision-making accuracy �1.78 1.54 .04 �.08 �.11* �.07 .14* �.14* .36* — Control variable 9. Distributive fairness 3.74 0.89 .22* .18* .04 .17* .31* �.35* .14* .12* — Note. N � 240. * p � .05, one-tailed. 642 COLQUITT tivism, though collective members were more affected by team- mates’ justice. Practical Implications These results suggest that the practical implications of proce- dural justice are more complex in team contexts. It is not enough to treat an individual member in a just manner in an effort to boost his or her role performance. As suggested in Figure 1, that practice could have a moderate benefit, a large benefit, or no benefit at all, depending on what happens to other team members. This is im- portant to consider, because many factors conspire to create in- consistent treatment within teams. For example, diversity in teams may create subtle differences in member treatment (Williams & O’Reilly, 1998). Alternatively, leader philosophies may dictate that information, influence, support, and attention be doled out on a dyad-by-dyad basis, as in leader–member exchange theories of leadership (Gerstner & Day, 1997; Graen & Scandura, 1987). Thus, some differences in treatment may be inevitable within teams, particularly in cases in which differences in function, status, or skill sets dictate differences in the control offered during pro- cedures. Obviously this situation creates a dilemma for managers in charge of teams in organizations. However, the results of Study 1 offer one practical suggestion: One must turn to other justice criteria to foster a more consistent perception of justice. Even when control must be varied, factors such as accuracy, bias sup- pression, and correctability can be made constant across team members. Indeed, past research has shown that leaders can be trained on such procedural rules in the interest of fostering positive workplace reactions (e.g., Skarlicki & Latham, 1996, 1997). Such training could allow leaders to more easily foster a consistent level of justice within teams. Leaders could also track and record that consistency using standardized measures of justice (e.g., Colquitt, 2001; Moorman, 1991). If differences in justice perceptions persist, then leaders should take greater care to explain any differences in treatment that could account for the variation. Past research has shown that explanations can mitigate negative reactions to unfavorable cir- cumstances (e.g., Bies & Shapiro, 1987; Greenberg, 1990; Rous- seau & Tijoriwala, 1999). A recent review showed that explana- tions are particularly effective when the outcome being explained has implications for a person’s economic and socioemotional Table 4 Moderated Regression Results for Study 2 Regression step Procedural fairness Conflict Cooperation Decision accuracy R2 �R2 � R2 �R2 � R2 �R2 � R2 �R2 � 1. Distributive fairness .09* .09* 0.31* .11* .11* �0.33* .02* .02* 0.12* .01 .01 0.11 2. Own justice .16* .07* 0.24* .12* .01 �0.09 .02 .00 �0.09 .02 .01 0.01 Others’ justice �0.10 0.00 0.00 �0.10 3. Own Justice � Others’ Justice .22* .06* 1.15* .12* .00 0.06 .05* .03* 0.70* .04* .02* 0.57* 4. TI .23* .01 �0.11 .13* .01 �0.01 .06* .01 �0.06 .06* .02 �0.12 ES 0.03 �0.13 �0.07 �0.08 5. Own Justice � TI .26* .03 �0.28 .17* .04* 0.48 .06 .00 �0.16 .08* .02 0.13 Others’ Justice � TI �0.45 0.42 0.10 �0.37 Own Justice � ES �0.47 �0.04 �0.16 �0.43 Others’ Justice � ES �0.48 0.67* �0.33 0.24 6. Own Justice � Others’ Justice � TI .28* .02* 0.14 .21* .04* �2.62* .10* .04* 2.71* .11* .03* 2.51* Own Justice � Others’ Justice � ES �3.82* 1.97* �1.88 �1.04 Note. N � 240. TI � task interdependence; ES � equity sensitivity. * p � .05. Figure 3. Own � Others’ Justice � Interdependence interaction for decision accuracy (Study 2). Figure 4. Own � Others’ Justice � Benevolence interaction for conflict (Study 2). 643REACTIONS TO PROCEDURAL JUSTICE well-being (Shaw, Wild, & Colquitt, 2003). Differences in proce- dural justice clearly hold both economic and socioemotional con- sequences for team members. Although the suggestions above are justice focused, team lead- ers could also turn to the moderators examined in this study. If treatment differences are unavoidable, the negative impact of those differences could be reduced by relaxing the level of task interde- pendence in the team. This could be accomplished by altering (a) the way the task is defined for the team, (b) the rules or instructions that are given to the team, or (c) the technology and skill compo- sition that characterize the team (Wageman, 2001). This option would be most effective when the level of interdependence out- paces the actual need for collective action. Alternatively, leaders could consider staffing the teams with individuals who are less equity sensitive. Personality measures are a standard component of most organizations’ selection, placement, and development sys- tems. Those existing systems could be expanded to include con- cepts such as equity sensitivity. Suggestions for Future Research Providing more specific recommendations for team leaders re- quires gaining a better understanding of the conceptual differenti- ation between own and others’ justice. With the exception of Study 1, every investigation of the interaction of own and others’ justice has manipulated treatment in a laboratory design. What is the relationship between the two constructs likely to be in actual team settings? The results from Study 1 suggest that the two are highly related, as the correlation between them was .69. The strength of this relationship is likely due to the two common causes the constructs share: the same formalized decision-making procedures and the same enactor of those procedures in the team leader. Several factors may impact the strength of the correlation be- tween own and others’ justice. First, different justice dimensions may possess different own– other correlations. Procedural justice is the most systemic of all of the justice dimensions, likely inflat- ing the own– other correlation. However, some procedural vari- ables may be more systemic than others. For example, Leventhal’s (1980) accuracy or correctability criteria may exhibit less within- team variation than Thibaut and Walker’s (1975) control-based criteria. Moreover, interactional forms of justice may exhibit larger differences within teams. For example, teams may possess cliques or in-groups that cause some members to receive more respectful treatment or to be more “in the know” because of frequent explanations. Team characteristics could also alter the relationship between own and others’ justice. Research examining justice at higher levels of analysis is indirectly relevant to this issue. Naumann and Bennett (2000) examined the relationship between procedural jus- tice climate and attitudes and behaviors in bank branches. Branches that were cohesive and possessed visible leaders tended to exhibit perceptual convergence with respect to justice climate (as evidenced by high within-group agreement or high interrater reliability). Colquitt et al. (2002) showed similar results for unit size and diversity, as large heterogeneous units tend to exhibit less climate convergence. These studies suggest that the relationship between own and others’ justice may vary across contexts even though both necessarily share common causes. Strengths and Limitations This study possesses a number of strengths. First, the multiple- study format allowed for two different operationalizations of pro- cedural justice and two different operationalizations of task inter- dependence. In addition, both studies used role performance as the dependent variable rather than the attitudinal outcomes used in past research. Moreover, the setting for Study 2 allowed for the creation of objective measures of both role performance and cooperation. Of course, these studies have their limitations as well. Although the teams in both studies possessed interdependence, common fate, and collective identity, they lacked the past history and familiarity of teams in organizations. It is therefore important to build on the results presented here by conducting field research in ongoing work teams. Although meta-analyses of the justice literature and other domains have indicated remarkable convergence in findings across lab and field studies (Anderson, Lindsay, & Bushman, 1999; Cohen-Charash & Spector, 2001), external validity can be established only by using several studies with varying methods, settings, and measures (Cook & Campbell, 1979). These studies also failed to include one common operationalization of procedural justice: the fulfillment of Leventhal’s (1980) rules for fair proce- dure. Future research should extend these results by examining the interaction of own and others’ levels of accuracy, bias suppression, correctability, or ethicality. Despite their limitations, these studies serve as an important first step in examining the full complexities of procedural justice in team contexts. The diversity in measures, research designs, and research settings offers some support for the replicability of the predicted interaction effects. It therefore seems clear that team members do not react to decision events on the basis of a tunnel- visioned awareness of only their own justice. Rather, they consider how that justice compares with that of their teammates, exhibiting more positive reactions when treatment is consistent within the team. References Adams, J. S. (1965). Inequity in social exchange. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (pp. 267–299). New York: Academic Press. Ambrose, M. L., Harland, L. K., & Kulik, C. T. (1991). Influence of social comparisons on perceptions of organizational fairness. Journal of Ap- plied Psychology, 76, 239 –246. Ambrose, M. L., & Kulik, C. T. (1989). The influence of social compar- isons on perceptions of procedural fairness. Journal of Business and Psychology, 4, 129 –138. Anderson, C. A., Lindsay, A. J., & Bushman, B. J. (1999). Research in the psychological laboratory: Truth or triviality? Current Directions in Psychological Science, 8, 3–9. Barnard, C. I. (1938). The functions of the executive. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Barrett-Howard, E., & Tyler, T. R. (1986). Procedural justice as a criterion in allocation decisions. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 50, 296 –304. Bies, R. J., & Moag, J. F. (1986). Interactional justice: Communication criteria of fairness. In R. J. Lewicki, B. H. Sheppard, & M. H. Bazerman (Eds.), Research on negotiations in organizations (Vol. 1, pp. 43–55). Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. Bies, R. J., & Shapiro, D. L. (1987). Interactional fairness judgments: The influence of causal accounts. Social Justice Research, 1, 199 –218. 644 COLQUITT Bliese, P. D. (2000). Within-group agreement, non-independence, and reliability: Implications for data aggregation and analysis. In K. J. Klein & S. W. J. Kozlowski (Eds.), Multilevel theory, research, and methods in organizations: Foundations, extensions, and new directions (pp. 349 – 381). San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. Cohen, S. G., & Bailey, D. E. (1997). What makes teams work: Group effectiveness research from the shop floor to the executive suite. Journal of Management, 23, 239 –290. Cohen-Charash, Y., & Spector, P. E. (2001). The role of justice in orga- nizations: A meta-analysis. Organizational Behavior and Human Deci- sion Processes, 86, 278 –321. Colquitt, J. A. (2001). On the dimensionality of organizational justice: A construct validation of a measure. Journal of Applied Psychology, 86, 386 – 400. Colquitt, J. A., Conlon, D. E., Wesson, M. J., Porter, C. O. L. H., & Ng, K. Y. (2001). Justice at the millennium: A meta-analytic review of 25 years of organizational justice research. Journal of Applied Psychology, 86, 425– 445. Colquitt, J. A., Noe, R. A., & Jackson, C. L. (2002). Justice in teams: Antecedents and consequences of procedural justice climate. Personnel Psychology, 55, 83–110. Cook, T. D., & Campbell, D. T. (1979). Quasi-experimentation: Design and analysis issues for field settings. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. Cropanzano, R., & Ambrose, M. L. (2001). Procedural and distributive justice are more similar than you think: A monistic perspective and a research agenda. In J. Greenberg & R. Cropanzano (Eds.), Advances in organizational justice (pp. 119 –151). Lexington, MA: New Lexington Press. Crosby, F. (1984). Relative deprivation in organizational settings. In B. M. Staw & L. L. Cummings (Eds.), Research in organizational behavior (Vol. 6, pp. 51–93). Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. Devine, D. J., Clayton, L. D., Philips, J. L., Dunford, B. B., & Melner, S. B. (1999). Teams in organizations: Prevalence, characteristics, and effec- tiveness. Small Group Research, 30, 678 –711. Earley, P. C. (1989). Social loafing and collectivism: A comparison of the United States and the People’s Republic of China. Administrative Sci- ence Quarterly, 34, 565–581. Earley, P. C. (1993). East meets West meets Mideast: Further explorations of collectivistic and individualistic work groups. Academy of Manage- ment Journal, 36, 319 –348. Earley, P. C., & Gibson, C. B. (1998). Taking stock in our progress on individualism-collectivism: 100 years of solidarity and community. Journal of Management, 24, 265–304. Folger, R. (1986). A referent cognitions theory of relative deprivation. In J. M. Olson, C. P. Herman, & M. P. Zanna (Eds.), Relative deprivation and social comparison: The Ontario symposium (pp. 33–55). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Folger, R. (1987). Reformulating the preconditions of resentment: A ref- erent cognitions model. In J. C. Masters & W. P. Smith (Eds.), Social comparison, justice, and relative deprivation: Theoretical, empirical, and policy perspectives (pp. 183–215). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Folger, R. (1993). Reactions to mistreatment at work. In K. Murnighan (Ed.), Social psychology in organizations: Advances in theory and research (pp. 161–183). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall. Folger, R., & Cropanzano, R. (1998). Organizational justice and human resource management. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Folger, R., & Cropanzano, R. (2001). Fairness theory: Justice as account- ability. In J. Greenberg & R. Cropanzano (Eds.), Advances in organi- zational justice (pp. 1–55). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Gerstner, C. R., & Day, D. V. (1997). Meta-analytic review of leader– member exchange theory: Correlates and construct issues. Journal of Applied Psychology, 82, 827– 844. Gibson, C. B. (1999). Do they do what they believe they can? Group efficacy and group effectiveness across tasks and cultures. Academy of Management Journal, 42, 138 –152. Gigone, D., & Hastie, R. (1997). Proper analysis of the accuracy of group judgments. Psychological Bulletin, 121, 149 –167. Gilliland, S. W., & Langdon, J. C. (1998). Creating performance manage- ment systems that promote perceptions of fairness. In J. W. Smither (Ed.), Performance appraisal: State of the art in practice (pp. 209 –243). San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. Graen, G. B., & Scandura, T. (1987). Toward a psychology of dyadic organizing. In L. L. Cummings & B. M. Staw (Eds.), Research in organizational behavior (Vol. 9, pp. 175–208). Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. Greenberg, J. (1990). Employee theft as a reaction to underpayment ineq- uity: The hidden cost of pay cuts. Journal of Applied Psychology, 75, 561–568. Grienberger, I. V., Rutte, C. G., & van Knippenberg, A. F. M. (1997). Influence of social comparisons of outcomes and procedures on fairness judgments. Journal of Applied Psychology, 82, 913–919. Guzzo, R. A., & Dickson, M. W. (1996). Teams in organizations: Recent research on performance and effectiveness. Annual Review of Psychol- ogy, 47, 307–338. Hackman, J. R. (1987). The design of work teams. In J. W. Lorsch (Ed.), Handbook of organizational behavior (pp. 315–342). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall. Hofstede, G. (1980). Culture’s consequences. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage. Hollenbeck, J. R., Colquitt, J. A., Ilgen, D. R., LePine, J. A., & Hedlund, J. (1998). Accuracy decomposition and team decision making: Testing theoretical boundary conditions. Journal of Applied Psychology, 83, 494 –500. Hollenbeck, J. R., Ilgen, D. R., LePine, J. A., Colquitt, J. A., & Hedlund, J. (1998). Extending the multilevel theory of team decision-making: Effects of feedback and experience in hierarchical teams. Academy of Management Journal, 41, 269 –282. Hollenbeck, J. R., Ilgen, D. R., Sego, D. R., Hedlund, J., Major, D. A., & Phillips, J. (1995). The Multilevel Theory of team decision making: Decision performance in teams incorporating distributed expertise. Jour- nal of Applied Psychology, 80, 292–316. Hui, C. H., Triandis, H. C., & Yee, C. (1991). Cultural differences in reward allocation: Is collectivism the explanation? British Journal of Social Psychology, 30, 145–157. Huseman, R. C., Hatfield, J. D., & Miles, E. W. (1987). A new perspective on equity theory: The equity sensitivity construct. Academy of Manage- ment Review, 12, 222–234. James, L. R. (1982). Aggregation bias in estimates of perceptual agree- ment. Journal of Applied Psychology, 67, 219 –229. James, L. R., Demaree, R. G., & Wolf, G. (1984). Estimating within-group interrater reliability with and without response bias. Journal of Applied Psychology, 69, 85–98. Johnson, D. W., Johnson, R. T., Buckman, L. A., & Richards, P. S. (1988). The effect of prolonged implementation of support within the classroom. Journal of Psychology, 119, 405– 411. Kiggundu, M. N. (1981). Task interdependence and the theory of job design. Academy of Management Review, 6, 499 –508. King, W. C., Jr., & Miles, E. W. (1994). The measurement of equity sensitivity. Journal of Occupational and Organizational Psychology, 67, 133–142. King, W. C., Jr., Miles, E. W., & Day, D. D. (1993). A test and refinement of the equity sensitivity construct. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 14, 301–317. Korsgaard, M. A., Schweiger, D. M., & Sapienza, H. J. (1995). Building commitment, attachment, and trust in strategic decision-making teams: The role of procedural justice. Academy of Management Journal, 38, 60 – 84. Lawler, E. E., Mohrman, S. A., & Ledford, G. E., Jr. (1995). Creating high 645REACTIONS TO PROCEDURAL JUSTICE performance organizations: Practices and results of employee involve- ment and total quality management in Fortune 1000 companies. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. Leventhal, G. S. (1976). The distribution of rewards and resources in groups and organizations. In L. Berkowitz & W. Walster (Eds.), Ad- vances in experimental social psychology (pp. 91–131). New York: Academic Press. Leventhal, G. S. (1980). What should be done with equity theory? New approaches to the study of fairness in social relationships. In K. Gergen, M. Greenberg, & R. Willis (Eds.), Social exchange: Advances in theory and research (pp. 27–55). New York: Plenum Press. Lind, E. A., Kray, L., & Thompson, L. (1998). The social construction of injustice: Fairness judgments in response to own and others’ unfair treatment by authorities. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 75, 1–22. Lind, E. A., & Tyler, T. R. (1988). The social psychology of procedural justice. New York: Plenum Press. Lindell, M. K., Brandt, C. J., & Whitney, D. J. (1999). A revised index of agreement for multi-item ratings of a single target. Applied Psycholog- ical Measurement, 23, 127–135. Mayer, R. C., Davis, J. H., & Schoorman, F. D. (1995). An integrative model of organizational trust. Academy of Management Review, 20, 709 –734. Miceli, M. P. (1993). Justice and pay system satisfaction. In R. Cropanzano (Ed.), Justice in the workplace: Approaching fairness in human resource management (pp. 257–283). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Miles, E. W., Hatfield, J. D., & Huseman, R. C. (1989). The equity sensitivity construct: Potential implications for worker performance. Journal of Management, 15, 581–588. Moorman, R. H. (1991). Relationship between organizational justice and organizational citizenship behaviors: Do fairness perceptions influence employee citizenship? Journal of Applied Psychology, 76, 845– 855. Moorman, R. H., & Blakely, G. L. (1995). Individualism– collectivism as an individual difference predictor of organizational citizenship behavior. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 16, 127–142. Naumann, S. E., & Bennett, N. (2000). A case for procedural justice climate: Development and test of a multilevel model. Academy of Management Journal, 43, 881– 889. Oyserman, D., Coon, H. M., & Kemmelmeier, M. (2002). Rethinking individualism and collectivism: Evaluation of theoretical assumptions and meta-analyses. Psychological Bulletin, 128, 3–72. Phillips, J. M. (2002). Antecedents and consequences of procedural justice perceptions in hierarchical decision-making teams. Small Group Re- search, 33, 32– 64. Phillips, J. M., Douthitt, E. A., & Hyland, M. M. (2001). The role of justice in team member satisfaction with the leader and attachment to the team. Journal of Applied Psychology, 86, 316 –325. Ramamoorthy, N., & Carroll, S. J. (1998). Individualism/collectivism orientations and reactions toward alternative human resource manage- ment practices. Human Relations, 51, 571–588. Rousseau, D. M., & Tijoriwala, S. A. (1999). What’s a good reason to change? Motivated reasoning and social accounts in promoting organi- zational change. Journal of Applied Psychology, 84, 514 –528. Saavedra, R., Earley, P. C., & Van Dyne, L. (1993). Complex interdepen- dence in task-performing groups. Journal of Applied Psychology, 78, 61–72. Shaw, J. C., Wild, R. E., & Colquitt, J. A. (2003). To justify or excuse?: A meta-analytic review of the effects of explanations. Journal of Applied Psychology, 88, 444 – 458. Shrout, P. E., & Fleiss, F. L. (1979). Intraclass correlations: Uses in assessing rater reliability. Psychological Bulletin, 86, 420 – 428. Skarlicki, D. P., & Latham, G. P. (1996). Increasing citizenship behavior within a labor union: A test of organizational justice theory. Journal of Applied Psychology, 81, 161–169. Skarlicki, D. P., & Latham, G. P. (1997). Leadership training in organiza- tional justice to increase citizenship behavior within a labor union: A replication. Personnel Psychology, 50, 617– 633. Steiner, I. D. (1972). Group process and productivity. New York: Aca- demic Press. Sundstrom, E., DeMeuse, K. P., & Futrell, D. (1990). Work teams: Ap- plications and effectiveness. American Psychologist, 45, 120 –133. Thibaut, J., & Walker, L. (1975). Procedural justice: A psychological analysis. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Triandis, H. C. (1995). Individualism and collectivism. Boulder, CO: Westview Press. Triandis, H. C., Bontempo, R., Villareal, M. J., Asai, M., & Lucca, N. (1988). Individualism and collectivism: Cross-cultural perspectives on self– group relationships. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 54, 323–338. Triandis, H. C., Leung, K., Villareal, M. J., & Clack, F. L. (1985). Allocentric versus idiocentric tendencies: Convergent and discriminant validation. Journal of Research in Personality, 19, 395– 415. van den Bos, K., & Lind, E. A. (2001). The psychology of own versus others’ treatment: Self-oriented and other-oriented effects on perceptions of procedural justice. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 27, 1324 –1333. Wageman, R. (2001). The meaning of interdependence. In M. E. Turner (Ed.), Groups at work: Theory and research (pp. 197–217). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Wagner, J. A., III. (1995). Studies of individualism– collectivism: Effects on cooperation in groups. Academy of Management Journal, 38, 152– 172. Waldman, D. A. (1997). Predictors of employee preferences for multirater and group-based performance appraisal. Group and Organization Man- agement, 22, 264 –287. Williams, K. Y., & O’Reilly, C. A., III. (1998). Demography and diversity in organizations: A review of 40 years of research. In L. L. Cummings & B. M. Staw (Eds.), Research in organizational behavior (Vol. 20, pp. 77–140). Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. Received August 5, 2002 Revision received July 12, 2003 Accepted September 15, 2003 � Instructions to Authors For Instructions to Authors, please consult the first issue of the volume or visit www.apa.org/journals/apl and click on Submission Guidelines. 646 COLQUITT work_3j4cdibcizaohgcjilkjhfruxu ---- Tax Competition and Global Background Justice Tax Competition and Global Background Justice Peter Dietsch Université de Montréal Département de Philosophie C.P.6128 succursale Centre-ville Montréal, QC, H3C 3J7, Canada E-Mail: peter.dietsch@umontreal.ca and Thomas Rixen Social Science Research Center Berlin (WZB) Research Unit: Transnational Conflicts and International Institutions Reichpietschufer 50 10785 Berlin, Germany E-Mail: rixen@wzb.eu Acknowledgments: For comments on previous drafts of this paper we thank Kim Brooks, Ryoa Chung, Matthias Ecker-Ehrhardt, Tim Gemkow, Monika Heupel, Dominic Martin, Mihaela Mi- hai, Jean-Pierre Vidal, Lora Viola, Daniel Weinstock, David Wiens, Jurgen de Wispelaere, and Michael Zürn. We acknowledge financial support from the DAAD (German Academic Exchange Service). Tax Competition and Global Background Justice Abstract In a globalized economy states compete for mobile tax bases. This tax competition undermines the fiscal self-determination of states and exacerbates inequalities of income and wealth both within countries and across borders. The paper provides a normative evaluation of the rules gov- erning international tax competition. We put forward two principles of international taxation de- signed to both protect and circumscribe the fiscal self-determination of states. First, a member- ship principle which holds that deriving the benefits of membership in any given country grounds an obligation to pay one’s taxes there. Second, an intentionality principle which states that any tax policy change is legitimate only if it would still be pursued in the counterfactual situation where the benefits of this move in terms of inflowing capital were absent. We then consider how the two principles can be implemented and propose to establish an International Tax Organization (ITO). This organization would have to be assigned institutional capacities very similar to those of the WTO in governing international trade. Finally, we show that our principles, despite being anchored in the fiscal self-determination of states, are compatible with a cosmopolitan position on global justice. They are principles of background justice in the sense that they define the rules of the game required for an international tax regime free of unjust bias. Keywords: Tax Competition, Global Justice, Background Justice, Self-determination, Institu- tional Design, Multi-level Governance. 1 Tax Competition and Global Background Justice A globalized economy raises intricate questions of distributive justice. Some of these have come under scrutiny in the literature. Under what conditions can international trade be regarded as respecting norms of fairness? Are wages at the subsistence level a necessary step on the path to growth or a form of exploitation? Who does and who should benefit from the profits generated by the exploitation of natural resources?1 Yet, one important determinant of global justice, namely questions of international taxation, has received little attention in the philosophical debate.2 While the importance of taxation as a means to implement domestic public policy and concep- tions of justice is widely acknowledged – and indeed often taken for granted – issues of interna- tional tax justice are mostly neglected. Tax competition between states puts pressure on domestic fiscal regimes. Mobile factors of production have the opportunity to “shop around” to minimize their tax burden. This interdependence of national tax regimes generates external effects that un- dermine the de facto sovereignty of states. As a consequence, tax competition tends to exacerbate inequalities of income and wealth both within countries and across borders. One way to address these issues is to condemn the distributive outcomes and to propose redis- tributive policies to correct what are perceived to be unjust inequalities. This approach is largely remedial. A second possibility is to examine the rules of the game of international taxation them- selves, and make sure they do not contain any unjust bias. This approach, which is geared to- wards the prevention of distributive injustice in the first place, is the approach favored here. To 1 See e.g. {Kurjanska, 2008 #3925;Risse, 2007 #3922}{Wenar, 2008 #3924}{Pogge, 2005 #3926} 2 There are, however, contributions from lawyers and economists discussing normative principles of international taxation, see e.g. {Musgrave, 1972 #690;Vogel, 1990 #109;Avi-Yonah, 2006 #931}. One exception in the philosophical literature is {Cappelen, 2001 #3793}. 2 what extent does the fiscal interdependence between countries call for a normative interdepend- ence in the form of obligations towards other countries that governments have to respect in their fiscal policy? How can we delineate legitimate fiscal interdependence from illegitimate tax com- petition? These are the questions that motivate this paper. They target the conditions of interna- tional background justice that need to be met to guarantee rules of international taxation that are free from any unjust bias.3 The core of the paper consists of two principles of international taxation designed to both pro- tect and circumscribe the fiscal prerogatives of the state.4 First, a membership principle which holds that deriving the benefits of membership in any given country grounds an obligation to pay one’s taxes there. Second, an intentionality principle which states that any lowering of national tax rates is legitimate only if it would still be pursued in the counterfactual situation where the external benefits of this move in terms of inflowing capital were absent. The paper is structured as follows. In a first step, we sketch the impact of tax competition on the de facto sovereignty of states as well as on social inequalities in order to explain why tax competition in its current form is a case of background injustice and should thus be on the radar of theories of justice (section 1). The central part of the paper then lays out the membership and intentionality principles (section 2). In section 3 we address the question of how these principles 3 See {Ronzoni, 2009 #3958}. The idea of background justice is discussed in detail in section 4 of the present paper. 4 Note that we only consider income taxes, so-called direct taxation. This is the area where tax compe- tition is fiercest. We do however also consider the effect of income tax competition on the structure of tax systems, e.g. the mix of direct and indirect taxes. Given that direct taxes are most sensitive to tax competi- tion, one may think that the easiest way to solve these issues is to rely more or solely on indirect taxes. This would however have adverse distributive consequences. See section 2. 3 could be implemented. We propose the establishment of an International Tax Organization (ITO) after the model of the World Trade Organization (WTO). We also endorse unitary taxation with formulary apportionment (UT+FA) as a reform of corporate taxation. Section 4 considers and rejects the potential objection that our account is incompatible with defending a cosmopolitan theory of global justice. Furthermore, it elaborates on the normative status of our account as one of international background justice. Section 5 concludes. 1. How Tax Competition Undermines Fiscal Self-Determination In this section we show that tax competition leads to policy changes that have not been legiti- mately chosen by the states involved, but were forced upon them by external competitive pres- sures. In other words, tax competition undermines the self-determination of states. We first ex- plain what fiscal self-determination entails and then how tax competition undermines it. The Content of Fiscal Self-Determination In order to establish the fiscal prerogatives of the state, it is useful to step back and consider what the purpose of taxation is. Among other things, it is needed in order to finance public goods.5 Due to collective action problems their provision generally requires a central enforcement institution, the state. Therefore the prior public good paid for by taxes is the state itself. The state can be viewed as a complex exchange between individuals in order to supply themselves with the public goods necessary to pursue their individual life plans. Under pluralism of conceptions of the good life, the legitimacy of the state is generally grounded in a democratic form of government, where those subject to the coercively enforced rules of the state are also the authors of these rules. 5 Other objectives of taxation include the redistribution of income and wealth as well as the setting of incentives or disincentives for certain kinds of economic behaviour. 4 Importantly, for the purposes of the present section, we take it for granted that polities should be granted considerable autonomy in designing their state institutions.6 In the fiscal context, a stylized definition of collective self-determination entails two basic choices concerning the size of the public budget (level of revenues and expenditures) and the question of relative benefits and burdens (extent of redistribution). While there are certainly many different views on how these two evidently interdependent choices ought to be made, there is widespread agreement that they constitute the fiscal prerogatives of the state.7 This is the substantive content of fiscal self- determination or tax sovereignty. Three points are worth mentioning. First, we make the simplifying assumption that govern- ments perfectly track their citizens’ preferences.8 We acknowledge that this is an unrealistic as- sumption, since government preferences often are the result of rather messy and conflictual po- litical processes, in which different groups of citizens pursue different interests. It is, in reality, not necessarily true that differences in political preferences within the polity of a state are less important than differences between polities.9 Second, a distinction needs to be made between de jure and de facto tax sovereignty. As will become clear in the next subsection, effective self- determination in fiscal matters requires the latter. Third, self-determination is not to be under- 6 We discuss the normative foundations of the (fiscal) self-determination of states in section 4. This or- ganisation of the paper reflects our emphasis on the content of the fiscal prerogatives of the state in an economically interdependent world. While the normative foundation of the state itself has to be addressed in this context, it is not at the heart of this paper. 7 {Cf. e.g. \Avi-Yonah, 2000 #516;Dietsch, 2008 #3637} 8 For a discussion of the problems associated with this assumption see {Cappelen, 2005 #3927@ 220- 22}. 9 Such situations raise questions about a possible reorganisation of the boundaries of states or of se- cession. See for instance {Buchanan, 2004 #3639} 5 stood in absolute terms. Instead, effective protection from illegitimate interference by other states requires limits on self-determination. Spelling out these limits lies at the heart of this paper. The Consequences of Tax Competition Tax competition is defined as interactive tax setting by independent governments in a non- cooperative, strategic way. For tax competition to exist there must be fiscal interdependence. This condition is met if tax bases are sensitive with respect to tax law differences, so that there is an effect of governmental actions on the allocation of mobile tax bases among jurisdictions. Tax base mobility must be legally possible and it must actually occur.10 Favorable tax conditions to attract foreign capital can be brought about in various ways, such as a reduction in tax burdens (be it by reducing tax rates or defining tax bases in favorable ways), fashioning preferential tax regimes for foreigners, or creating (or not closing) tax loopholes, e.g. through implementing bank secrecy rules or a lax enforcement of existing rules. Tax competition primarily targets capital, which is mobile internationally.11 Governments use different strategies and tax instruments depending on the kind of capital targeted. Three kinds of capital can be distinguished. First, in the area of portfolio capital of individuals and firms, so- called tax havens often have low or zero tax rates. More importantly, they offer strict bank se- crecy rules as well as certain legal constructs such as trusts that enable individuals to hide their ownership vis-à-vis tax administrations in their state of residence. While it is hard to come up with reliable figures since tax evasion is illegal, the available evidence suggests that there is a real 10 {Wilson, 2004 #571@ 1065-6} 11 In general, labor is quite insensitive to tax differentials and thus the fundamental requirement of fis- cal interdependence is hardly met. However, this is not true for certain high-skilled segments of the labor market. We bracket tax competition for labor here. 6 effect of these policies. Estimates of the worldwide yearly revenue losses to government coffers range from 155 to 255 Billion USD.12 Second, governments compete for foreign direct investment (FDI) in the form of real business activity, e.g. location decisions of multinational enterprises (MNEs). These business decisions depend on various factors such as the level of education, the costs of labor, and the quality of the infrastructure. But the effective tax burden also plays a role. Empirical studies come to the con- clusion that raising taxes decreases the inflow of foreign direct investment. However, the direc- tion and strength of the correlation is strongly affected by the method of measurement and the kinds of tax rates investigated.13 In their quest to attract foreign direct investment, governments may either lower the general business tax rate or they can engage in designing so-called preferen- tial tax regimes, which grant tax advantages to foreigners only (ring fencing). Third, there is competition for so-called paper profits. Through various techniques, such as transfer pricing (especially of intangible assets) and thin capitalization, MNEs can assign profits made in high-tax countries to their subsidiaries in low-tax countries without relocating real busi- ness activity.14 Despite different approaches, all empirical investigations into this issue come to the same conclusion: the transfer of taxable profits is very sensitive to taxation, and companies make ample use of these possibilities. The decisive factor to attract mobile profits is the nominal tax rate, because companies shift only those profits that cannot be offset against depreciation and 12 {Owens, 2007 #2749;Tax Justice Network (TJN), 2005 #1831} 13 {de Mooij, 2008 #3635} 14 For a description of these and other techniques of shifting paper profits, see e.g. {, 1995 #330@ 8- 17} The fact that 60% of world trade is intra-firm indicates that the tax base at stake is significant. 7 other tax benefits.15 Again, governments may also decide to compete via specially designed re- gimes to attract paper profits. For example, the regime of Special Financial Institutions (SFI) in the Netherlands allows foreign companies to channel capital through them in order to realize tax benefits. Standard theory predicts a “race to the bottom” in capital taxation and the under-provision of public goods in all jurisdictions.16 While this extreme outcome cannot be observed empirically, it can be shown that tax competition undermines the fiscal self-determination of states, i.e. their ability to effectively set the size of the budget and the extent of redistribution. In OECD coun- tries, nominal corporate tax rates have fallen from an average of around 50% in 1975 to an aver- age below 30% in 2005. Over the same period, nominal top personal income tax rates have fallen from around 70% to well below 50%. These rate cuts were refinanced by broadening the bases on which taxes are applied (‘tax cut cum base broadening’). In this way, corporate tax revenue re- mained stable at an average of about 2.5% of GDP, whereas income tax revenue as a percentage of GDP rose from 11.2% to 12.8% of GDP.17 The trend towards low nominal tax rates and broad tax bases is an attempt to defend against the outflow of mobile profits and at the same time pre- vent an adverse revenue effect.18 15 {Devereux, 2006 #1951;de Mooij, 2008 #3635} The fact that profit shifting is possible may explain the weaker effect of tax policies on FDI. As long as MNEs can realize tax savings without business reloca- tions, the competition for FDI and mobile profit is in a substitutive relationship. We return to this issue in part 2. 16 {See e.g. \Wilson, 2004 #571@ 1069-70} 17 {OECD, 2008 #3170} 18 {See e.g. \Haufler, 2000 #1436} 8 While revenue losses did not occur, the ‘tax cut cum base broadening’ policy affects the dis- tribution of the tax burden among different kinds of taxpayers. For one, there is an effect within the business sector: highly profitable MNEs benefit, while nationally organized small and me- dium-sized enterprises are more heavily burdened. Second, the tax burden is shifted from capital to labor. This is also visible in the general trend to increase indirect taxes, such as consumption taxes.19 Last but not least, competitive downward pressure on corporate tax rates affects the dis- tributional characteristics of the personal income tax. If the nominal corporation tax rate is low- ered, then it is worthwhile for private individuals to re-label their income by incorporating. In order to prevent such arbitrage, policy makers often align the corporate tax rate and the top rate on personal income, thus flattening the personal income tax schedule.20 As to developing countries, the dynamics of a race-to-the-bottom have a more visible impact. The pressure from tax competition on public finances is comparable to OECD countries, but de- veloping countries usually do not have the administrative resources to stabilize their revenues by broadening their tax base. On the contrary, in many countries the base has been narrowed.21 A significant part of the revenue loss is directly due to the shifting of paper profits. One study esti- mates the annual revenue loss of developing countries from transfer pricing to be US $ 160 bil- lion.22 19 {Loretz, 2008 #3668;Schwarz, 2007 #1953;Genschel, 2002 #190} 20 {Ganghof, 2006 #1435} 21 {Keen, 2004 #1872} 22 {Christian Aid, 2008 #2701} 9 Overall, the empirical evidence shows that tax competition undermines fiscal self- determination.23 While states still possess the formal right to set tax policies (de jure sover- eignty), they cannot effectively pursue their desired policy goals (de facto sovereignty). Devel- oped countries are able to maintain the size of the budget (first component of self-determination), but this can only be achieved by compromising the desired extent of redistribution and making the tax system more regressive (second component of self-determination). By contrast, develop- ing countries are not able to prevent revenue losses and thus lose both components of fiscal self- determination. In this respect, tax competition increases existing inequalities between countries of the global North and South. For these reasons, we consider international tax competition in its present form to be a case of background injustice. In the absence of an institutional framework to regulate it, it introduces multiple kinds of bias into the international fiscal regime that lack justifi- cation. 2. Two Principles of International Background Tax Justice: Membership and Intentionality The last section has specified the content of fiscal self-determination and demonstrated how it is endangered by tax competition. Just like in the case of individual liberty, to be effective, the lib- 23 Some observers argue that the policy choices described above – tax cuts cum base broadening, in- creasing reliance on indirect taxes and low tax burdens on capital – are not caused by tax competition. They argue that these policies reflect a general shift towards market-conforming taxation that governments implemented irrespective of competitive pressures. {cf. e.g. \Steinmo, 2003 #1432} While it is true that there are also domestic efficiency reasons for implementing these policies, our foregoing sketch of the mechanisms shows – in line with most of the public finance literature – that these changes are to a signifi- cant part driven by the pressures of tax competition. For more on this debate, see {Rixen, 2007 #1312}. If, however, as we will discuss in section 2, such policies are indeed chosen for domestic reasons only, they would not indicate a violation of self-determination but an instance of it. 10 erty to make these collective choices is restricted by the same liberty for the citizens of other countries. The two principles we will advance in this section spell out these restrictions and are meant to ensure that countries have an effective right to tax that reflects their polities’ choices about the size of the state budget and the desired extent of redistribution. The membership princi- ple is based on the intuition that capital mobility renders this liberty fragile and that it therefore needs to be protected. The intentionality principle argues that this liberty can be abused and therefore calls for it to be circumscribed. The Membership Principle Imagine you live on a street with two fitness clubs. One high-end club with expensive equipment and all kinds of free-bees like club towels and shaving equipment, and one less fancy club that lacks the rowing machines, has only three Stepmasters instead of ten and no free-bees. Unsurpris- ingly, the membership fee of the high-end club is almost three times that of its no-frills competi- tor. You are a member of the no-frills club. One day, you discover that your membership card actually lets you pass the turnstile at the high-end club, too. You keep quiet and start working out there. As it turns out, quite a few members of the no-frills club frequent the fancy club. A month later, you bump into a friend in the washrooms of the high-end club. “What are you doing here?” he asks. With a sheepish look on your face, you tell him about your discovery. He is enraged: “You guys are free-riding on our membership fees.” He informs the manager and, the next day, the high-end club starts issuing new membership cards. This reaction appears justified and serves to stop what was an unacceptable form of free-riding. For the purposes of our argument, the analogy between countries and clubs is a useful one. There are places, e.g. the Scandinavian countries that provide more services like state-financed daycare, more generous unemployment insurance, and so on, but in turn also “charge” more in 11 terms of taxes.24 There are others, like England, where citizens prefer to have a leaner set of serv- ices and hence pay less. Certain forms of tax planning that involve shifting one’s tax base to a low-tax jurisdiction without moving the underlying activity itself are parallel to using the high- end fitness club on your no-frills card. When a company uses the services of a country – that is its infrastructure, the human capital, and so on – to produce a certain commodity, but then shifts the paper profit made with this economic activity to low-tax jurisdictions through practices like trans- fer pricing or thin capitalization, the citizens who finance these services have a legitimate com- plaint. Tax evasion by individuals, as suggested by its illegality, represents an even blunter form of abuse. This is like jumping the turnstile at the high-end fitness club when no one is watching. Despite these parallels between the membership in a fitness club and a country, the reaction of free-riders when they are found out is rather different. Whereas it seems reasonable to expect most people to feel sheepish about free-riding at the high-end fitness club, the parallel practice at the level of countries is often pursued without shame and, in the case of corporate tax avoidance, even under the approving stamp of legality. This reaction can be explained, but not excused, by the pervasive perception of taxation as something that the state takes away from us rather than as part of a social compact between citizens.25 We are now in a position to formulate our first principle of international taxation, the member- ship principle: 24 We put “charge” in inverted commas here, because we do not mean to imply adherence to the benefit principle. See also discussion below. 25 {Murphy, 2002 #2485} call this phenomenon the “myth of ownership.” They argue that citizens do not have an entitlement to their pre-tax income but can only claim legitimate ownership to their post-tax income since the tax-financed state defines property rights in the first place. 12 Natural and legal persons should be liable to pay tax in the state of which they are a mem- ber. In order to apply the principle, it is necessary to define membership. Our definition is the fol- lowing: Individuals and companies should be viewed as members in those countries where they benefit from the public services and infrastructure.26 This conception of membership is related to, but distinct from, what is called the “benefit principle” or the principle of “fiscal equivalence” in the public finance literature.27 The benefit principle is sometimes contrasted with the ability to pay principle.28 Whereas the latter justifies redistribution, the former does not and makes taxes strictly proportional to the individual benefits taxpayers receive in return. Our conception of membership is more general and comprises both of these principles. It is compatible with what has been called “group fiscal equivalence”29, which demands that the collective benefits of the 26 While, as we will briefly discuss below, this definition of membership is not detailed enough to re- solve all cases of ambiguous membership assignments, it does nonetheless exclude certain conceptual possibilities. It should be emphasized, for example, that our definition of membership is distinct from citizenship. Permanently non-resident citizens should not be liable to tax in their country of citizenship. Conversely, temporary resident aliens, even though they generally do not have a democratic voice in state decisions, should be. Moreover, companies should not be given voting rights. In the case of individuals, consider a person living and working in a country for one or two years. It seems justified to tax her, but also permissible not to give her a say in democratic decisions. In fact, one could sensibly distinguish between different thresholds of permanence. Whereas a tourist should not be liable to income tax in the country he visits, a “guest worker” staying for longer than, say, 6 months should be. For a resident alien taxpayer to acquire voting rights, the level of permanence can be signifi- cantly higher – even though it seems to us that many countries are too restrictive in granting citizenship to permanently resident foreigners. We bracket these debates here. 27 {Olson, 1969 #268} 28 See e.g. {Slemrod, 2004 #1630@ 61-6} 29 {Thielemann, 2002 #3525} 13 group of citizens should be proportional to the amount of taxes paid. It thus allows for redistribu- tion among individuals. As implicit in our notion of fiscal self-determination, the citizens of a state may well decide that it is appropriate to tax people with higher incomes at higher rates. On this issue, the above analogy between the fitness clubs and countries breaks down. True to its objective to re-establish the de facto sovereignty of states, the membership principle is silent on the actual tax system chosen by polities. It merely stipulates that polities should have an effective right to tax individuals and companies benefiting from public services and infrastructure as they see fit. Our definition of membership is broad enough to encompass the major intuitions of diverse theories of international taxation. In the international tax literature, there is agreement that a nexus between the taxpayer and the country is required for tax membership. Yet, there is dis- agreement about the proper nature of the nexus – should it be economic, social, political or terri- torial allegation, or a combination of these? The disagreement has never been fully resolved at the level of principles.30 This is unsurprising, given that each pure solution has distributive con- sequences which favor the material revenue interests of certain groups of countries over others. Most importantly, developing countries, as capital importers, favor taxation at source, i.e. in those countries where capital is invested. In contrast, capital exporting countries favor residence taxa- tion, i.e. in those countries where investors reside. This conflict has shaped the history of interna- tional taxation and continues to do so.31 30 See e.g. {Musgrave, 1991 #144}{Biehl, 1982 #1406}{Cappelen, 2001 #3793} 31 See e.g. {Musgrave, 1972 #690}{Vogel, 1990 #109}{Rixen, 2008 #2123@ 57-116} 14 Nevertheless, a working compromise has been found. According to the so-called “interna- tional tax principles”32 individuals are assessed on a residence basis, because residence deter- mines where they benefit from public services and where they should therefore be counted as a member. Companies benefit from public services and infrastructure in the country where their substantive activities take place. Beyond a certain threshold of economic activity, they are there- fore liable to tax in source countries, i.e. those countries in which the income was generated. For MNEs whose activities spread across borders, membership comes in degrees and should corre- spond to the distribution of its economic activities among countries. This justification for the combination of the residence and source principle of international taxation is commonly ac- cepted. While the detailed definition of membership for particular cases remains a thorny and often controversial issue, which keeps many tax experts busy, the distribution of taxing rights broadly follows this pattern, which is in line with our membership principle. However, there are two problems. First, even though their underlying rationale is in line with our membership principle, the actual international tax rules, which are made up of domestic tax laws, bilateral double tax agreements (DTAs) and non-binding model conventions of interna- tional organizations, create certain overlaps (so-called double taxation) and gaps (double non- taxation) in countries’ taxing rights33. As described in section 1, these grey zones can be ex- 32 {Avi-Yonah, 2006 #931} Avi-Yonah argues that the existing rules of international taxation make up a coherent “international tax regime”. 33 For example, a few countries, most importantly the US, tax not only their residents but also their non-resident citizens. Some countries apply different rules if an individual has multiple residences (typi- cally, an individual counts as a resident for tax purposes if she spends 183 days or more in the country). In some instances, countries disagree over what counts as a sufficient economic activity to warrant taxation at source. For a discussion of the gaps and overlaps in the international tax regime with references to the vast legal and economic literature on the topic, see {Rixen, 2008 #2123@ 66-85} 15 ploited by sophisticated taxpayers to minimize their tax bill, and thus violate the membership principle. Second, even if there were no scope for manipulation, the current rules are badly en- forced. There is no international authority guarding countries’ adherence to the rules, and admin- istrative assistance and information exchange among national tax authorities is underdeveloped. This makes it possible for taxpayers to escape the taxman and is a violation of the membership principle. How would respecting the membership principle change the international tax landscape? While the detailed answer depends on the way it is institutionalized, a general answer can be given. The membership principle ensures that tax competition is actually in line with Tiebout’s notion of “voting with your feet.”34 Tiebout’s model is generally presented as a justification for tax competition. It is argued that competition among jurisdictions leads to an efficient allocation of public funds as individuals self-select into different jurisdictions offering certain tax- expenditure packages according to the extent to which these match their fiscal preferences. A crucial assumption of the model is that there are neither positive nor negative externalities on other countries stemming from the provision of “local” public goods. This assumption will gen- erally not hold in reality.35 While the costs and benefits of government action will never align perfectly in an economically interdependent world, the membership principle works to minimize the gap between them. It prohibits the hiding or shifting of part of the tax base from one’s resi- dence in the case of individuals and from the source of the economic activity in the case of multi- nationals. In order to realize tax advantages, companies and individuals would actually have to 34 {Tiebout, 1956 #277} 35 Most defences of the status quo of tax competition assume Tieboutian sorting to work efficiently {see e.g. \Mueller, 1998 #262}. Given the reality of externalities and capital shifting, it is easily apparent that such arguments cannot hold {Sinn, 1997 #274}. 16 relocate, rather than merely shifting their funds. Free-riding would no longer be possible. In other words, two of the three kinds of competition, shifting of mobile profits and competition for port- folio capital would be curtailed. The crucial question in assessing the potential impact of the membership principle is how in- dividuals and companies would react if these possibilities were no longer available. To what ex- tent would individuals and companies make use of their exit option, and move or relocate their residence or real economic activity from high-tax to low-tax jurisdictions? For an assessment of this issue, it is useful to consider individuals and MNEs separately. Individuals form a certain attachment to the place they live in. This attachment often includes the internalization of the solidarity that is reflected in their polity’s choices about the size of the state and the extent of redistribution. Having said that, it is evident that in people who evade taxes in their home country, this internalization has not happened. If their affective ties to the country are not strong enough to compensate the losses that respecting the membership principle imposes on them relative to the status quo, then some individuals may indeed choose to leave. Note, how- ever, that this decision will also incur a cost. Whereas under the status quo they are able to free- ride by evading taxes, under the membership principle leaving a high-tax country for a low-tax one implies receiving fewer government services. A company, by contrast, cannot form affective ties to a particular location. Its managers make the decision of where to locate its different economic activities according to what maximizes profit rather than according to the affective ties of employees. This means we can expect the reac- tion of companies to enforcing the membership principle to be more significant than that of indi- viduals. Under the status quo, the pressure on an MNE to leave a high-tax jurisdiction is low, since the loopholes in the current system enable it to shift some of its profit instead and thereby 17 lower its effective tax burden. A shift from the status quo to a world where the membership prin- ciple is respected would be a shift from a world of (merely) virtual tax competition for paper profits to a world of real tax competition for FDI: companies would have to relocate real invest- ment in order to realize tax savings. It has been argued that such real tax competition may be more harmful to high-tax states than virtual tax competition. Instead of loosing only tax revenue, high-tax states stand to lose real capital and jobs as well.36 Apparently, some politicians in high-tax countries have resigned to the fact that, in the absence of fundamental international tax reform, tolerating profit shifting is their best strategy.37 Unsur- prisingly, this acceptance is not reflected in the official political discourse since it would mean admitting to voters that one is letting some people free-ride. What we observe today in the prac- tice of corporate taxation, in other words, is a system of nominal tax competition with price dif- ferentiation. It is as if a high-end fitness club nominally charges a high membership fee to cover its costs, but then secretly gives rebates to certain customers it does not want to lose. Since it is an empirical question how the world of real tax competition would play out, it remains unclear whether the above stance of policymakers is warranted. It may well be that companies requiring state-of-the-art infrastructure or access to high-skilled labor will choose high-tax countries, whereas companies in labor-intensive, low-skill sectors will move to low-tax jurisdictions. In any case, from the perspective of the membership principle any relocation of real invest- ment in the case of companies and of residence in the case of individuals would be unproblem- atic. The membership principle ensures that taxes are paid where the benefits from public serv- ices and infrastructure are obtained and thus effectively addresses two of the three types of tax 36 {Keen, 2001 #3847;Dharmapala, 2008 #3283@ 671-6} 37 Cf. {Rixen, 2011 #3907} 18 competition – the targeting of portfolio investments as well as of paper profits. In the next section we explain why this is not enough to preserve fiscal self-determination, and why there is also a need to constrain competition for ‘real’ FDI. The Intentionality Principle Independently of how distribution plays out in a world that respects the membership principle, the question arises whether this principle suffices as a condition of justice in international taxa- tion. To demonstrate why we think that the membership principle on its own would be insuffi- cient to adequately protect fiscal self-determination, let us return to a more sophisticated version of our story about fitness clubs. Suppose the fitness clubs, though on the same street, fall on two sides of a municipal bound- ary. Suppose also that you can only become a member of a fitness club if you are resident in the respective municipality – this assumption guarantees that the membership principle is respected. About 20% of the population is a member in a fitness club. Since they are in better shape, fitness club members find it much easier to move house from one municipality to another. The financing structure of both clubs is 80% through membership fees and 20% through subsidies from the mu- nicipality, i.e. through municipal taxes. One day, the manager of the low-end fitness club has an idea. He lobbies the mayor to increase the municipality’s subsidy to cover 40% of the costs of running the club. This allows the club to lower membership fees and the municipality to attract new residents. Since the services offered by the club remain the same, the lower price will con- vince some of the members of the high-end club that the difference in price is now too big to jus- tify the service premium their club offers. They move to the municipality of the no-frills club 19 (MN-F) and become members there.38 Subsequently, in order to compensate the decline in reve- nues from membership fees, the high-end club will have to either also obtain a larger share of its financing from its municipality (MH-E) or reduce the quality of its service. Is there anything wrong with this from the perspective of justice? The short answer is: It de- pends. We will argue that the legitimacy of this move depends on the motives behind the change of policy in MN-F. Against the background of section 1, the parallel between the fitness club case and tax competition between countries is straightforward to see. In the above story, for fitness club users, read mobile factors; for non-club members, read immobile factors; for mayor, read government. The altering of the financing structure at the no-frills club corresponds to a broaden- ing of the tax base and a shift of the tax burden to relatively immobile factors. To see why it will be necessary to appeal to the intention of the mayor of MN-F to decide whether the new policy poses a problem, consider the following two scenarios. In scenario A, the majority of residents see the new financing structure as the just way to fund the club, and conse- quently the mayor pushes for the policy change. Given the right of a polity to choose the size of their state and the extent of redistribution established in section 1, it is only consistent to consider the policy as legitimate in this case. In scenario B, the new policy is adopted, because it will al- low the municipality to attract new residents and the corresponding tax base. The two scenarios are observationally equivalent. Hence, if one wanted to make a case that scenario B poses a nor- mative problem, one would have to appeal to a non-consequentialist criterion that tracks the dif- ferent motives. 38 To make this plausible, let us assume that club membership fees represent a significant part of peo- ple’s budget. 20 So why should we think anything wrong with scenario B in the first place? Reconsider the last sentence of the fitness club story: “Subsequently, in order to compensate the decline in revenues from membership fees, the high-end club will have to either also obtain a larger share of its fi- nancing from its municipality or reduce the quality of its service.” The external effect of the pol- icy change in MN-F represents a violation of the liberty of the residents in MH-E to choose their preferred size of the budget and extent of redistribution. Under scenario A, we have to choose between restricting the right of residents in MN-F to exercise their liberty versus restricting the right of residents in MH-E to exercise theirs. By contrast, under scenario B, the right of residents in MH-E to exercise their liberty trumps the purely strategic considerations of MN-F. This is the basis for condemning the policy change under scenario B. To summarize in the language of coun- tries rather than fitness clubs, if a country changes its tax system merely in order to attract tax base from abroad, this conflicts with the rights to fiscal self-determination of other countries and is therefore problematic from a normative viewpoint. These considerations motivate our second principle of justice for international taxation, the in- tentionality principle: Suppose the benefits of a tax policy change in terms of attracted tax base from abroad did not exist, would the country still pursue the policy under this hypothetical scenario? If yes, the policy is evidently not motivated by strategic considerations and therefore legitimate. If not, then the policy is illegitimate. “Strategic” here implies that a policy is justified by the prospect of attracting mobile capital from abroad rather than by appeal to the fiscal prerogatives of the state defined in section 1. The counterfactual nature of the criterion allows us, on a conceptual level, to elicit the motivation of a 21 country in pursuing any given fiscal policy.39 It effectively delineates (legitimate) fiscal interde- pendence from illegitimate tax competition.40 Note that it also captures cases of mixed motives. Suppose a country lowers a certain tax rate in part because this reflects the conception of justice of its citizens, but also because of the strategic value of doing so for attracting foreign tax base.41 Perhaps the country would, in the absence of the inflowing tax base from abroad, still lower the rate in question, but by a lesser amount. In this case, that lesser reduction is motivated by legiti- mate motivations, whereas the part of the reduction that would be dropped is illegitimate. Someone might object that such an attempt to discern different motives suffers from two im- portant ambiguities, even on a theoretical level. First, suppose the citizens of a developing coun- try are motivated by social justice reasons to build more hospitals and, in order to do so, decide to lower their country’s taxes to attract the necessary capital from abroad. Is this part of their fiscal self-determination or should it count as a strategic consideration? In the latter case, would we not deprive poor countries of an important source of redistribution? We believe that our principle can answer these questions. First, we submit that this policy should indeed count as motivated by strategic considerations. Capital that is attracted to the developing country to build a hospital is not available to build a hospital elsewhere. Second, this does not mean that building the hospital in the developing country is not important and does not exclude the possibility that richer coun- tries have an obligation of assistance towards this project. But this obligation should not be dis- 39 The counterfactual nature of the criterion is in part inspired by {Normore, 2010 #3928} on the foun- dations of political obligation. 40 Remember from the definition provided in section 1 that the strategic motivation is a necessary ele- ment of tax competition. Thus, by eliminating strategic motivations, none of the remaining fiscal interde- pendence qualifies as tax competition. 41 As explained in footnote 23, such mixed motives are empirically plausible. 22 charged in the form of a bias in the way the jurisdictional structure of international taxation is set up. It should rather be dealt with on the level of the allocation of collective revenues – for in- stance in the form of a unitary tax with formulary apportionment as discussed below – or via ex- plicit redistribution. Conversely, this means that rectifying the jurisdictional structure of interna- tional taxation should be conditioned on developed countries fulfilling their redistributive obliga- tions towards developing countries.42 Second, one may ask whether our intentionality principle applies to all potential policy in- struments with cross-border effects. Do we rule out strategic behavior across the board, or are there instances in which they are legitimate? Our answer is that it depends on whether the strate- gic interaction, i.e. competition, will lead to a race to the bottom or whether it can be seen as harmless or even as a race to the top. Take the example of strategic infrastructure investments. A country invests in high-quality and specialized infrastructure in order to attract high-tech busi- nesses from abroad which form a highly interdependent cluster. Due to agglomeration effects this will positively impact growth in the country. As a reaction to that other countries may also begin 42 In fact, this issue is not simply hypothetical. There is a debate about the legitimacy of developing country (often small island) tax havens. When OECD countries began to pressure tax havens to abandon their harmful tax policies (see below), some tax havens argued that they had chosen to become tax havens because they saw no other possibility to initiate economic development. In fact they argued that the rich countries are hypocritical wanting to close down the (offshore) financial centres, the development of which they had earlier advocated. See {Sharman, 2006 #1998}. In fact, we agree that those developing countries have a right to adequate compensation by ‘high-tax’ countries if our two principles are imple- mented. Such a right would, however, not be awarded to rich, longstanding tax havens like Switzerland, Liechtenstein and others. 23 to specialize in certain infrastructures and form such clusters. The result is likely to be a race to the top – in which case there is no need to rule out strategic considerations.43 Given that a large part of the literature considers tax harmonization to be the relevant alterna- tive to tax competition, two observations should be made in this regard. First, in a world where both the membership and the intentionality principle are respected there would not be full har- monization of fiscal policies across countries. Suppose the English really do have a preference for a smaller state and less redistribution than the Swedish. Neither of our principles will stop them from designing a tax structure that reflects these preferences. In turn, nothing we have said will prevent the Swedes from making a democratic choice that the best way to finance a relatively generous welfare state is to shift a considerable portion of the tax burden onto labor and con- sumption and to tax capital lightly. There may indeed be good internal reasons for such a pol- icy.44 However, the intentionality principle prohibits the very same policies if they are based on strategic considerations. Second, even in a world where different polities have divergent preferences about the size of the state and the extent of redistribution, our two principles will create some pressure towards convergence. This is so because countries with preferences for a relatively large state and/or high extent of redistribution will now have to bear the real costs of these preferences in terms of part of their tax base voting with its feet. At the other end of the spectrum, however, the danger of a race to the bottom would be eliminated by our two principles for the very same reason. Countries 43 This is not to deny that some attempts of strategic infrastructure investment may turn out to be un- successful. However such individual failures do not contradict the fact that from the collective viewpoint the competitive dynamic is beneficial. 44 See e.g. {Przeworski, 1988 #704} 24 with smaller state budgets and a lower level of redistribution would also be forced to bear the full costs of their tax structure, rather than being able to finance part of their public services by strate- gically attracting foreign tax base. The fiscal externalities generated in both directions under the intentionality principle are those minimally present under conditions of fiscal interdependence between states. They ensure a maximum – though less than perfect – correspondence between the convictions of members of the respective polities and fiscal structure of those polities. The intentionality principle entails that different fiscal communities have to justify their policy choices to one another. Whether a given change in tax structure is just or not depends on how the country in question justifies this change to others. The intentionality principle complements the membership principle and fills the normative void where the membership principle on its own would fall short in adequately protecting fiscal self-determination. Despite these attractions of the intentionality principle, it also faces two related objections. First, why try to elicit the intentions of polities and their governments in fiscal policy when the market mechanism arguably offers a shortcut to the same outcome? After all, one of the main attractions of the mechanism of competitive markets is the fact that it serves to promote the common good irrespective of the individual intentions of market participants. Should this mecha- nism not also be at work in the case of tax competition? The answer to this question is no. In con- trast to a competitive market where private goods are traded, tax competition is about public goods. As Hans-Werner Sinn has shown, tax competition amounts to trying to provide public goods via the market mechanism.45 As every first-year economics student knows, this is ineffi- cient and therefore detrimental to the common good. If, at the same time, we do not want to cen- tralize the decision for the provision of public goods at the highest level (world government), but 45 {Sinn, 1997 #274} 25 want to allow for some diversity among decentralized units (states), then it is necessary to elimi- nate the strategic element of interactions between these units. This is what our intentionality prin- ciple does. Yet, condemning the market alternative is not sufficient to endorse our proposed alternative. According to the second objection, the fact that intentions are unobservable stands in the way of making the principle operational. Our response to this challenge is twofold. First, we acknowl- edge that this is a serious problem. Second, however, we think that it is a necessary problem in the sense that any approach that aims to delineate illegitimate tax competition from mere fiscal interdependence will encounter it. Whether we are right about this or not hinges on the previously discussed question of whether the legitimacy of a given tax policy depends on the motivation that drives the policy. Recall our suggestion that it is possible to have two observationally equivalent scenarios. Under scenario A, the policy change flows from the preferences of citizens about the size of the state and the extent of redistribution. Under scenario B, the change is strategically mo- tivated. If you agree that these should be evaluated differently from a normative perspective, then you should also agree that appealing to motivation is a necessary component of a normative ac- count of international taxation. In this case, the challenge of the second objection is pushed back to the institutionalization of our principles that we will turn to now. 3. Institutionalizing the Two Principles It is notoriously difficult to derive concrete institutions from abstract principles. This is so even in the absence of ambiguity about what the correct interpretation of the principle is, because there will generally be more than one way to institutionalize a principle. In the face of this institutional indeterminacy, we limit ourselves here to demonstrating that there is an institutional solution that 26 satisfies the conditions embodied in our principles. As a further caveat, we stress that the follow- ing brief sketch cannot, due to space constraints, do full justice to the complex issues of interna- tional taxation. But it should suffice to outline the institutional implications of our proposal. Any institutional solution must provide (1) a forum for governments to negotiate agreements on the rules of international taxation and (2) make sure that the rules are enforced. In the follow- ing we propose the establishment of an International Tax Organization (ITO) and discuss the ba- sic institutional design features required for the two tasks.46 We have already stated that it is nec- essary for governments to come to a multilateral agreement on what it means to be member of a state and that the details of such a rule will be controversial. The ITO should become a forum for negotiating and defining the rules in line with the membership and intentionality principles. To ensure a level-playing field, all states should be members and adequately represented in the ITO’s decision-making procedures. The OECD as today’s most important international tax forum is often criticized for falling short in these respects. We first discuss a possible institutionalization of the membership principle and then turn to the intentionality principle. Third, we propose en- forcement mechanisms. Last, we provide a brief comparative analysis between current institu- tions and policy initiatives in international taxation on the one hand and the hypothetical world in which our two principles are respected on the other in order to gauge to what extent the latter is an improvement over the status quo. 46 Calls for an International Tax Organization can be found in the literature, see {e.g. \Tanzi, 1999 #98;Horner, 2001 #822} However, so far no attempt has been made to derive the institutional design from the functional requirements of the issue to be dealt with. On institutional design, see e.g. {Koremenos, 2001 #519} 27 Institutionalizing the Membership Principle On the basis of our two principles several substantive reforms become imperative. First, the membership principle requires governments to abolish all rules that make it impossible for other countries to enforce the membership principle. Thus, strict bank secrecy regulations, the supply of other deliberately nontransparent legal constructs and the refusal to exchange information with other tax administrations will be ruled out. This means that governments must internationally commit themselves to rid their national tax codes of all such secrecy rules. The requirement to exchange tax-relevant information with other countries could be implemented through a system of multilateral automatic exchange of information. Automatic information exchange would repre- sent a significant improvement upon on-request information exchange, which is currently pro- vided for in many bilateral tax treaties. Under the on-request system, the requesting state will generally have to present initial evidence of international tax evasion in order to receive the re- quired information about foreign funds of its residents. Yet, precisely the kind of information required to mount an initial case is often secret. Routine and electronic (i.e. automatic) exchange of information on the funds of non-residents to their respective home countries can address this problem.47 Second, an ITO with inclusive membership would provide an ideal forum to reconsider the membership rule in the case of MNEs. How should the rights to tax shares of the profit of an MNE be allocated among jurisdictions? This issue is a very thorny one in international tax prac- tice that has so far been resolved through so-called separate entity accounting and arm’s length 47 For more on automatic and multilateral exchange of tax information, see {Spencer, 2005 #3749} and {Palan, 2010 #3868@ 244-45} 28 standard (ALS) transfer pricing.48 However, as set out in section 1, both the indeterminacy of applying this standard and the difficulties in its enforcement can be exploited by MNEs to lower their tax bills. One possible solution would be to switch to a system of unitary taxation with for- mula apportionment (UT+FA). This would require governments to agree on a common and con- solidated corporate tax base. MNEs would have to determine their worldwide profit in one single report, and they would be allowed to consolidate profits and losses of entities in different coun- tries. The worldwide profit would then be apportioned to the respective countries in which the MNE operates on the basis of a predetermined formula. The formula should reflect the real eco- nomic activity in each country by referring to factors such as property, sales, and payroll. This would make it impossible for companies to engage in the shifting of paper profits and thus be a major step forward in the implementation of the membership principle.49 Institutionalizing the Intentionality Principle As we have already acknowledged, defining rules that respect the intentionality principle will be difficult. The fact that intentions are unobservable invites hypocrisy. It will be possible for gov- ernments to misrepresent their intentions, i.e. attribute any tax policy changes to the preferences of citizens about the size of the state and the extent of redistribution, even if in reality they pursue the strategic aim of attracting foreign tax base. In order to avoid hypocritical political discourses and long but futile attempts to distinguish honest from dishonest representations of intentions, the 48 According to the ALS, foreign branches or subsidiaries of an MNE are to be taxed as if they were independent market participants, exchanging goods and services at arm’s length (i.e. market) prices, see e.g. {Eden, 1998 #838@ 32-52} 49 There is an extensive literature in law and public finance on UT+FA and how it compares to separate entity accounting. For an overview, see e.g. {Graetz, 2003 #816@ 400-35}. Two different proposals to implement UT+FA, are {Clausing, 2007 #2668} and {Rixen, 2007 #2001} 29 institutionalization of the principle has to rely on objectively observable factors. The task is to identify observable implications of the unobserved intentions. While a detailed and legally applicable definition of objective factors that indicate a violation of the intentionality principle is a task for tax lawyers and thus beyond the scope of this paper, it is nonetheless possible to derive a number of rules that are in line with the intentionality princi- ple. First, all forms of preferential tax regimes for foreigners (ring fencing) must be abolished. Such discriminatory arrangements show that a government implements a policy for strategic rea- sons only because otherwise it would grant equal treatment to residents and non-residents alike. Note, however, that non-discrimination, while it covers part of our intentionality principle is not sufficient to constrain all forms of strategic and harmful policies. As is well known in the public finance literature, relatively small countries are in a position to overcompensate revenue losses from general (i.e. non-discriminatory) rate decreases with inflowing foreign tax base.50 We therefore need to supplement the non-discrimination rule with additional observable criteria to further constrain purely strategic behavior. 51 Enforcement What would it take to effectively enforce our two principles? First, we argue that monitoring the adherence to the rules should be relatively straightforward since governments can be expected to launch a complaint if other governments violate either or both of the two principles.52 Yet, what 50 See e.g. {Bucovetsky, 1991 #1035}{Dehejia, 1999 #193} 51 Comments on this aspect of the paper are particularly welcome. 52 That said, it may be in the interest of governments to assign the ITO with the task to collect and pro- vide information on tax policy changes to all member countries. This would make the tax policies of indi- vidual countries common knowledge of all countries and would thus greatly increase transparency. 30 is needed is an independent authority that will process the complaint and eventually enforce the rules. Independent third party enforcement is needed to ensure compliance with the two princi- ples, because the structure of tax competition is such that every individual country has an incen- tive to deviate from the collectively desirable rules. The ITO could install a dispute settlement procedure after the WTO model to satisfy this requirement.53 In case a member state complains that the tax practices of another member violate the rules, they can, as a first step, try to resolve the conflict in consultations. If they are unsuccessful, the case will be transferred to the dispute settlement body (DSB), which effectively functions like an independent judiciary, because a panel report (judgment) can only be blocked if all member states unanimously agree on blocking it. If the DSB considers the policy a violation of the rules, the government will have to revoke the policy. If it does not do so, it will have to pay a fine to the ITO. Since parties know that there will be effective enforcement of decisions in the DSB, it can be expected that they will resolve many cases in consultation. This procedure has the advantage of avoiding excessive litigation in the implementation of the rules and leaves room for political negotiations and decisions. The contrast with the status quo How does our proposal for the future rules of international taxation compare with the status quo? As we have described in part 1, the current situation is characterized by harmful tax competition. This fact has not gone unnoticed by governments and international organizations. Accordingly, they have launched policy initiatives to address this situation. The most prominent of these initia- tives is the OECD project to counteract harmful tax competition.54 The original purpose was to 53 For a descripotion of the WTO dispute settlement process, see e.g. {Zangl, 2008 #3579} 54 {OECD, 1998 #836}. 31 persuade tax havens to abolish harmful tax practices. In particular, they were encouraged to change their national tax laws so that it would no longer be possible for a tax avoider to merely ‘book’ some economic activity in the respective haven without any underlying ‘real’ economic activity. Also, they were asked to give up bank and tax secrecy legislation and to open up for information exchange with other states. In addition to the tax havens, the project also aimed at so- called preferential tax regimes in OECD countries, i.e. rules which tried to attract foreign capital by offering better treatment than was available to domestic investors. Since the OECD has no authority to issue binding rules, it pursued a “naming and shaming” approach and published a blacklist of tax havens and preferential tax regimes that should be evaluated and removed in a process of peer reviews.55 The initiative has not been successful. The criterion of missing substantial economic activity was removed from the definition of tax havens56, who can continue to offer tax residence to cor- porations and individuals even if there is no real economic activity linked to the tax base. Instead, the OECD now merely advances certain standards of transparency and information exchange between tax havens and non-haven countries.57 Importantly, this decision took the issue of tax avoidance and planning, which make up a significant part of tax competition, off the agenda. More transparency and better information exchange merely target outright illegal tax evasion.58 And even evasion is not effectively addressed, since the OECD relies on bilateral information exchange agreements which provide for exchange on request only, which has significant short- 55 {OECD, 2000 #51} 56 {OECD, 2001 #52`, 10} 57 {OECD, 2004 #568} 58 {Webb, 2004 #860`, 816}. 32 comings (see above). Even after the financial crisis, when the G 20 instructed the OECD to re- invigorate its project, there were no major improvements. The OECD continued its efforts to get countries to sign bilateral information exchange agreements.59 This does of course nothing to ameliorate the major shortcoming, i.e. the ineffectiveness of exchange on request. The OECD initiative’s failure can be attributed to successful campaigns of low-tax countries who claimed that any restrictions on their tax policy initiatives represent undue interferences into their fiscal sovereignty60 and successful campaigns by business lobbies who succeeded in captur- ing their governments with threatening to exit were they to be deprived of tax planning opportu- nities.61 The European Union has been somewhat more successful in its initiatives against harmful tax competition. With respect to business tax competition, the Council agreed on a soft law Code of Conduct in 1997. Like the OECD project, this Code of Conduct was also aimed at harmful tax competition. Member states entered into a non-binding commitment to remove so-called prefer- ential tax regimes, i.e., schemes that offer more generous tax treatment to foreign corporations than to domestic businesses. Despite its being non-binding, the code developed some bite because compliance with it was made a condition of accession for the Central and Eastern European coun- tries. Also, the Commission applied the principles contained in the code to its state aid rules, 59 As of 1 July 2011, 477 information exchange agreements had been signed (http://www.oecd.org/document/7/0,3746,en_2649_33767_38312839_1_1_1_1,00.html). 60 {Sharman, 2006 #1998} 61 {Webb, 2004 #860}{Rixen, 2011 #3907} 33 which thus increased compliance among the EU-15 states.62 Currently, the European Union con- siders adopting a system of unitary taxation with formula apportionment.63 In the area of portfolio tax competition the EU has passed the Savings Tax Directive, which took effect in July 2005.64 This directive targets tax evasion on interest income by requiring automatic information exchange among countries on the savings of foreign residents. Some tax havens, jealously guarding their bank secrecy, have opted to apply a withholding tax rather than to exchange information. While the directive has significant loopholes – notably it can be cir- cumvented by moving funds to third countries, it applies only to interest income so that it can be circumvented by restructuring portfolios from debt to equity and it is not applicable to trusts or corporations – it is important in that it shows that automatic international information exchange can be implemented in practice. Our proposal significantly improves upon these initiatives. In line with the normative demands of our two principles we propose an international framework that is much stronger than the cur- rent international tax institutions, which cannot make binding rules and, as the case of the OECD project shows, lack international levers of enforcement. The experience at the regional level of the European Union shows that this is indeed feasible. The EU uses one of the specific policies we recommend, namely automatic information exchange, and is seriously debating another one, UT+FA. At the same time, note that our proposal, while it does involve a redefinition of fiscal sovereignty, does not require the transfer of core fiscal prerogatives to the international level. No supra-national power to tax is established. Instead, the idea is that the international community 62 {Radaelli, 2008 #2553`, 327-8}{Genschel, 2011 #2688, 12-3} 63 {European Commission, 2011 #4293} 64 On this initiative see {Rixen, forthcoming #4086} 34 can impose certain limits on the fiscal choices of nation states ex post. In order to implement this, we propose the establishment of an International Tax Organization, which supervises countries’ tax policies and has the capacity to effectively sanction harmful national tax policies. The exis- tence of the WTO is testament to the fact that it is achievable. 4. Toward what Kind of Global Justice? We have pointed out that the membership and intentionality principles serve to protect the de facto sovereignty of states and their capacity to implement the conception of justice of their citi- zens domestically through their fiscal policy. Yet, what about global justice? Arguably, the most disturbing inequalities in today’s world are ones between individuals across borders rather than between citizens of the same state. Our account owes two explanations in this context. First, we need to justify granting states fis- cal self-determination in the first place – a question that we bracketed in section 1. Prima facie, it might seem that doing so puts our account at odds with a number of theories of global justice, notably cosmopolitan ones. We will show that this is not the case. Second, a clarification con- cerning the normative status of the two principles is in order. In the second part of this section, we will elaborate on what we have in mind when presenting them as principles of international background justice. The Normative Grounds of Self-Determination Consider the following formulation of the basic tenet of cosmopolitanism: “Moral cosmopolitan- ism holds that all persons stand in certain moral relations to one another: we are required to re- spect one another’s status as ultimate units of moral concern – a requirement that imposes limits 35 upon our conduct and, in particular, upon our efforts to construct institutional schemes.”65 Moral cosmopolitanism is to be distinguished from legal cosmopolitanism, which calls for a global or- der in which people have “equivalent rights and duties.”66 While the latter, more radical version of cosmopolitanism is indeed incompatible with state autonomy, most cosmopolitan theorists endorse the more moderate variant of the cosmopolitan ideal.67 It is not our goal here to endorse cosmopolitanism or any other theory of global justice. We merely aim to anticipate and counter the objection that the membership and intentionality princi- ples and the self-determination of states they advocate conflict with moral cosmopolitanism as defined above. To this end, we will now sketch three ways in which a moral cosmopolitan may accept, or even endorse, the self-determination of states. First, a cosmopolitan may hold that “to respect one another’s status as ultimate units of moral concern” actually requires a certain level of state autonomy.68 How so? Consider a purely justice- based cosmopolitan theory, i.e. one that proposes one theory of global justice to apply to all hu- man beings across the globe. Such a position runs into the objection of pluralism concerning con- ceptions of justice. Given pluralism, so the objection against this position runs, imposing one conception of justice on everyone in fact fails to respect those who do not share it as ultimate units of moral concern. This objection can be defused by introducing a democracy-based compo- nent into cosmopolitanism. This component requires that people have a say in the decisions that affect their interests. Note that this does not provide us with a justification for the self- 65 {Pogge, 1992 #2834} 66 Ibid. 67 They include {Beitz, 1999 #4284}, {Caney, 2006 #3641}, {Tan, 2004 #3937}, {Moellendorf, 2002 #4285}, {Pogge, 2008 #4286} 68 {Caney, 2006 #4287} defends an argument of this sort. 36 determination of states as such, but for a multi-level governance structure that states plausibly form a part of. Under this structure, political issues are dealt with at the governance level that best corresponds to the scope of the policy in question – for example, environmental issues will be dealt with at a higher level of governance than questions of educational policy. The upshot of this position is what Simon Caney calls a mixed cosmopolitan view that is sensitive both to a minimal – i.e. pluralism-defying – notion of global justice and to the importance of political participation. A position of this type accepts a certain level of state self-determination on normative grounds. While certain constraints based on considerations of global justice may apply to the level of self- determination in question, there is no incompatibility with the membership and intentionality principles as such. Second, a cosmopolitan may defend state self-determination as the most effective means to promote the interests of individuals worldwide. In particular, he may believe it to offer a more effective way of serving these interests than concentrating collective decision-making at the highest level, i.e. in the hands of a world government. As Robert Goodin puts it, the special du- ties that states have towards their citizens are the best way of discharging “the general duties that everyone has towards everyone else worldwide.”69 Besides, granting autonomy to states offers protection from domination as well as immunity from the larger unit that allows it to be more responsive to local interests and to reduce the burdens of decision-making.70 A position of this type accepts a certain level of state self-determination on instrumental and conditional grounds. If it turns out that there is an institutional alternative that serves the interests of individuals 69 {Goodin, 1988 #3935@ 681} 70 These are some of the classic reasons given for a federal structure. In addition, the existence of sev- eral smaller units allows for different experiments of life. See e.g. {Follesdal, 2001 #3938@ 251-53;Oates, 1999 #265} 37 worldwide in a better way, the justification of self-determination is undermined. The same quali- fication would apply to an endorsement of the membership and intentionality principles on these grounds. Finally, for those cosmopolitans who remain unconvinced by the two previous arguments, there is another, pragmatic reason to grant states some autonomy nonetheless. A theory of justice with practical ambitions is well advised to take some features of the world as given, rather than attempting to reform everything at once. Arguably, the division of world politics into states is a good candidate for such a feature, given that a world without states has to be viewed as utopian from today’s perspective. Note that adopting a pragmatic stance of this kind does not imply accepting the current state system as just. One might argue that those states benefiting from the international structure in unjust ways incur a series of redistributive obligations towards those who get short-changed un- der the status quo.71 We agree that such redistributive duties exist today. However, this paper relegates them to the background. Our focus here has been to design fair rules of the game to govern the fiscal interdependencies between states. It is to a series of comments on the normative status of these rules that we turn in the next subsection. In sum, the cosmopolitan has at least three potential reasons to accept the kind of state self- determination implicit in our membership and intentionality principles. While we do not defend a 71 For instance, countries can have redistributive duties towards the members of other states because they unduly benefit from economic interaction with them, see {Parijs, 2007 #2933}; or because they have inflicted harm on them in the past, see {, 2002 #3640}; or simply because the latter find themselves unable to survive without outside assistance. This list is not meant to be complete. 38 particular theory of global justice in this paper, accepting these two principles does not impose an undue constraint on the position one may want to defend in this regard. An account of background justice in international taxation The literature on global justice has been dominated by questions concerning the relation between principles of domestic justice versus principles of global justice. While cosmopolitan theorists generally defend continuity between the two,72 their critics hold that the global sphere is signifi- cantly distinct from the domestic level.73 One of these alleged differences will preoccupy us here, namely the question of whether a global basic structure exists that gives rise to concerns of global distributive justice.74 On the one hand, a number of so-called “practice-dependent” views argue, first, that the con- tent of our conceptions of justice is dependent on the practices they regulate and, second, that no clear structures and rules of the required kind exist at the global level to give rise to concerns of distributive justice.75 On the other hand, this position has recently been contested in two ways. First, Andreas Follesdal has argued that several of the practices of international relations are in 72 See for instance the following two review articles: {Caney, 2001 #3918} and {Parijs, 2007 #2933} 73 To cite some of the most important positions of this kind, the global sphere is argued to be distinct due to its lack of a global people (e.g. {Miller, 2007 #4288}), its lack of a global democracy (e.g. {Nagel, 2005 #2833}), or its lack of a global state (e.g. {Blake, 2001 #3644}). 74 John Rawls defines the basic structure of society as “the way in which the major social institutions distribute fundamental rights and duties and determine the division of advantages from social cooper- ation.” {Rawls, 1999 #4289@ 6}. Here, we are interested in the global basic structure. 75 See for example, {Sangiovanni, 2007 #2822}, and {Meckled-Garcia, 2008 #4290} While we dis- tance ourselves from one aspect of their position here, a lot more would have to be said to do their contri- bution justice. 39 fact constitutive of a global basic structure and, hence, that issues of global justice do indeed arise.76 Second, and more importantly in our context, Miriam Ronzoni has suggested that “the most pressing issue is not whether we have a global basic structure, but whether we need one.”77 Ronzoni makes the case that the absence of a global basic structure in the face of inequalities should not lead us to conclude that these inequalities somehow fall outside the purview of justice, but instead calls for the creation of such a basic structure. Internationally as well as domestically, certain rules may be required to guarantee the fairness of interactions between individuals. Ron- zoni submits that “under circumstances of intense international interaction and interdependence the conditions of effective sovereignty, and hence of international background justice, may be eroded.”78 Consequently, she advocates the creation of functionally differentiated supranational institutions that have the (legitimate) authority to set certain rules for appropriate conduct. This is precisely the kind of claim we have attempted to substantiate with respect to interna- tional tax competition in section 1. The current institutional setting undermines effective sover- eignty. The membership and intentionality principles are designed to restore this sovereignty and to guarantee international background justice. In fact, Ronzoni explicitly cites tax competition as one policy area where she considers international background justice to be violated and calls for interdisciplinary research on this issue. Delivering on the research program of international back- ground justice in international taxation is the principal objective of this paper. Let us add two comments on this categorisation of our account as one of international back- ground justice. First, in line with Ronzoni’s account as well as with our remarks in the introduc- 76 Cf. {Follesdal, 2011 #4291}. 77 {Ronzoni, 2009 #3958@ 243} 78 {Ronzoni, 2009 #3958@ 248-49} 40 tion to this paper, the idea of background justice emphasizes institutional reform over redistribu- tive obligations. It favours preventative institutional reform to remedial redistribution of income. That said, note that our two principles will go some way towards reducing global inequalities. For those who agree that we are currently facing a situation of background injustice, the inequalities that would be eliminated by institutional reform of the kind proposed here in fact qualify as injus- tices. What is more, neglecting institutional reform at the expense of an exclusive focus on redis- tribution amounts to a Sisyphus task. Redistribution to correct for an institutional bias and injus- tice is analogous to swimming against the current – it takes a lot more energy while getting you less far. Second, this short section cannot claim to present a comprehensive treatment of the rich litera- ture on global justice. Our limited objective here has been to elucidate the nature of our contribu- tion to the literature. The membership and intentionality principles represent principles of interna- tional background justice. 5. Conclusion Portraying the tax and transfer branch of government as the major instrument of redistribution can obscure the fact that competition between different tax systems will in fact exacerbate in- come inequalities both domestically and globally. This paper was motivated by the intuition that the inequality-enhancing effects of tax competition can be qualified as unjust. The membership and intentionality principles defended above serve as a normative toolkit to identify what that portion is. They specify to what extent the interdependence of states in fiscal matters calls for normative interdependence. To put these principles into practice, we propose the creation of an International Tax Organization (ITO), whose job description would include the settling of dis- 41 putes between states about which tax policies violate the membership and intentionality princi- ples. To be sure, a world in which the membership and intentionality principles are respected is not yet a just world. It is merely a world that guarantees international background justice in two im- portant ways. First, national polities would regain the capacity to make collective fiscal choices about the size of the state and the level of domestic redistribution. In other words, the member- ship and intentionality principles ensure that the costs of fiscal choices fall on those who make them, at least to the extent that this can be achieved under conditions of fiscal interdependence. Second, the two principles will have to be complemented by substantive principles of global tax justice. While these necessarily build on the work done in this paper, they also ask the question whether states have normative obligations to make transfer payments to other states and, if so, what they are. We hope to address this issue in future work. work_3jinxmlijzhydnm4hlw7kmohie ---- 209 1988-7221 | Vol. 9 | Nº 1 | 2016 | pp. 209-234 Esta obra está bajo una licencia de Creative Commons Reconocimiento-NoComercial 3.0 Unported. Justicia de transición en España: claves para aprobar una asignatura pendiente Transitional Justice in Spain Universidad de Oviedo, España lucpayero@gmail.com Abstract justice put forward by L. Joinet –truth, justice and reparation– will frame this analysis. Firstly, the protection of human rights, as agreed within the specialized literature, would be met. Key words: Francoist crimes, International Criminal law, Transitional justice in Spain, Amnesty Law, Historical memory, Spanish transition Resumen El objetivo de este trabajo es analizar la política española en materia de justicia transicional. To- mando como referencia las tres dimensiones de la justicia de transición señaladas por L. Joinet - ción, serán sugeridas algunas medidas que, de adoptarse, acercarían a España a lo que la literatura especializada considera que son los estándares internacionales en materia de protección de los Derechos Humanos. Palabras clave: Crímenes franquistas, Derecho internacional penal, Justicia de transición en España, Ley de Amnistía, Memoria histórica, Transición española http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/3.0/deed.es_ES mailto:lucpayero@gmail.com artículos originales Payero López, Lucia. Justicia de transición en España: claves para aprobar una asignatura pendiente210 1. La Transición española Tras la muerte de Franco se inicia en España un proceso de transición a la democracia que culmina con la aprobación de la Constitución de 1978. La española puede ser adecuada- mente descrita como una transición «vía transacción», puesto que se trata de un supuesto en el que una dictadura «inicia la transición estableciendo ciertos límites al cambio políti- co y permaneciendo como una fuerza electoral relativamente significativa a lo largo de la [misma]» (Share y Mainwaring, 1986: 88). Se lleva a cabo una negociación «generalmente implícita entre las elites del régimen autoritario y [de] la oposición democrática», por lo que las partes mantienen una desigualdad de partida: «el régimen [dictatorial] toma la iniciativa de dar comienzo a la liberalización1 y durante la mayor parte del proceso per- manece en una posición que le permite ejercer una influencia significativa sobre el curso del cambio político» (1986: 88). Ello condujo a que el saldo final del proceso beneficiase a quienes comenzaron con ventaja, puesto que ellos diseñaron las líneas maestras del ré- gimen democrático de acuerdo a sus intereses. He aquí algunos ejemplos. En primer lugar, la monarquía impuesta por Franco en la persona de Juan Carlos de Borbón se mantuvo hasta hoy sin que el pueblo fuera consultado acerca de la forma de gobierno que prefería –a pesar de que el sistema democrático inmediatamente anterior era el de la II República– ni se exigiera al monarca que jurase la Constitución –quien, por el contrario, prometió respetar las Leyes Fundamentales del Reino hasta en dos ocasiones–. Incluso cuando Juan Carlos decidió abdicar en su hijo para lavar la cara a una institución salpicada por los escándalos no se planteó seriamente la necesidad de dotar de legitimidad democrática a la monarquía a través de la celebración de un plebiscito. En segundo lugar, las líneas generales del sistema electoral actual ya se contenían en el Real Decreto-ley 20/1977, de 18 de marzo, que establecía las normas rectoras del proceso para la elección de las Cortes que habrían de aprobar la Constitución. Condicionados por la Ley para la Reforma Política,2 los contenidos del Decreto-ley de 1977 tendrían continuación en la Constitución y en la Ley Electoral.3 A grandes rasgos, puede afirmarse que el diseño del sistema electoral español consagra el bipartidismo, otorga mayor peso a las provincias escasamente pobladas y rurales, de tendencia conservadora, y sólo arroja resultados proporcionales en las circunscripciones de mayor tamaño, actuando como un procedimiento cuasi-mayoritario en el resto. Todo ello conduce a que el sistema produzca unos efectos psicológicos que tienden a reforzar sus efectos materiales (el llamado «voto útil»). Como consecuencia aparece un sentimiento generalizado de ausencia de alterna- tivas y, por tanto, cunde la sensación de que la mayor parte de los ciudadanos no están representados por las opciones políticas que gobiernan. En tercer lugar, la unidad nacional resultó de una imposición extraparlamentaria sin cuya aceptación los militares no hubiesen permitido que el proceso de elaboración cons- 1. Lo que no quiere decir que lo hiciera de manera voluntaria: «los cambios se dan en respuesta a la gran moviliza- ción popular» (Monedero, 2013: 136). 2. Ley 1/1977, de 4 de enero, para la Reforma Política. 3. Ley Orgánica 5/1985, de 19 de junio, del Régimen Electoral General. Revista de Paz y Conflictos issn 1988-7221 | Vol. 9 | Nº 1 | 2016 | pp. 209-234 211 titucional continuara (Solé Tura, 1985: 99-100). Más aún, se encomienda al ejército la defensa de esa unidad nacional. En cuarto lugar, y aunque se ha dicho que la Constitución española permite una interpretación tendencialmente socialista o más neoliberal, lo cierto es que no estamos ante un texto constitucional revolucionario o rupturista –como la Constitución italiana de 1948 o la portuguesa de 1976–, sino ante una Constitución mixta. Y es que «en las transiciones vía transacción acometidas por regímenes autoritarios conservadores cabe esperar que los líderes del régimen gobiernen evitando cambios socioeconómicos de orden estructural» (Share y Mainwaring, 1986: 95). Eso se consiguió en España a través de los Pactos de la Moncloa, que fijaron «las paredes maestras del modelo económico» (Pisare- llo, 2011: 178). La evolución posterior hacia una mayor liberalización de los mercados y una paralela reducción de los derechos sociales vendría marcada por la incorporación a la Comunidad Económica Europea en 1986. El resultado fue la consagración de «una auténtica Constitución económica dirigente, pero invertida, que regulaba con detalle su programa tecnocrático y neoliberal, frenando cualquier intento de regeneración demo- crática y proscribiendo la posibilidad de que dentro de los Estados pudieran ejecutarse políticas keynesianas capaces de contener al capital financiero» (Pisarello, 2011: 186). La crisis económica actual y la reforma del artículo 135 de la Constitución para dar prioridad al pago de la deuda sobre cualquier gasto social o de otro tipo terminaron por dibujar los rasgos de la Constitución económica en España. En quinto lugar, y a los efectos de este trabajo, reviste una importancia fundamental otra característica típica de las transiciones vía transacción, como es «la ausencia de me- didas de castigo dirigidas contra los líderes del periodo autoritario» (Share y Mainwaring, 1986: 95). Se puede entender que los líderes de un régimen dictatorial se nieguen a iniciar «la democratización a no ser que les sea garantizado el que no vayan a ser procesados» (1986: 95), pero lo que llama la atención del caso español es que transcurridos casi cua- renta años desde la aprobación de la Constitución, con un sistema de democracia formal plenamente consolidado, sigan sin adoptarse apenas medidas de justicia de transición. Y ello a pesar de los recientes desarrollos del Derecho internacional en materia de pro- tección de las víctimas de violaciones de Derechos Humanos y desapariciones forzosas. Más aún, el discurso oficial acerca de la Transición en España afirma que representó un proceso modélico, digno de ser exportado a otras latitudes4 y que, aunque tuvo sus ligeras sombras, éstas aparecen compensadas por sus muchas luces y se explican acudiendo al 4. Según Elster, «el caso español es único dentro de las transiciones a la democracia, por el hecho de que hubo una decisión deliberada y consensuada de evitar la justicia transicional […]. En los hechos esta decisión consensuada de ignorar el pasado no tuvo imitadores directos» (2006: 80-81). Es más, los únicos ejemplos que pueden extraerse de ella son la «impunidad de grandes criminales, la mentira, el silencio, el abandono y desprecio a las víctimas de la represión» (Sáez, 2010: 30-31). artículos originales Payero López, Lucia. Justicia de transición en España: claves para aprobar una asignatura pendiente212 contexto de terrible confrontación social5 de la época.6 No obstante, un estudio compa- rativo del caso español y otros supuestos transicionales permite comprobar que existen modelos alternativos en los que, al contrario que en España, se aplicaron medidas de jus- ticia de transición de manera más amplia y efectiva y se procedió a recuperar la memoria democrática anterior a la dictadura. A continuación analizaré con detalle los déficits que presenta la justicia transicional en España para intentar demostrar que, lejos de resultar ejemplar, la Transición española consagró un modelo de impunidad para los criminales de la dictadura. En lugar de ser exportada, la Transición española debiera ser revisada y sus errores, en la medida de lo posible, enmendados.7 2. Justicia de transición en España El término justicia de transición (transitional justice) hace referencia a «la variedad de pro- cesos y mecanismos asociados con los intentos de una sociedad por resolver los problemas derivados de un pasado de abusos a gran escala, a fin de que los responsables rindan cuen- tas de sus actos, servir a la justicia y lograr la reconciliación. Tales mecanismos pueden ser judiciales o extrajudiciales» (Naciones Unidas, 2004: §8). Es importante destacar que las medidas de justicia transicional no sólo resultan de aplicación en sociedades en las que se está gestando la democracia –como sería España a mediados de los años setenta–, sino que Estados con un sistema democrático asentado, al menos desde un punto de vista formal –como la España actual– también pueden –y deben– recurrir a ellas a fin de saldar cuentas con su pasado. Tras el informe de Joinet sobre la impunidad de los autores de violaciones de los De- rechos Humanos, se suele entender que la justicia de transición se compone de tres di- mensiones: verdad, justicia y reparación (1997). Veamos en qué consiste cada una de ellas. 2.1. Verdad El principio de verdad tiene como finalidad esclarecer los hechos ocurridos durante la dictadura para determinar si constituyeron una vulneración de los derechos fundamenta- les. La verdad, en este sentido, presenta una doble dimensión: individual y colectiva. En el 5. Algunos elementos de ese contexto que permiten comprender mejor el desarrollo de la Transición española –aun- que sus hagiógrafos no siempre los señalen– son, además de la violencia y la conflictividad social, la crisis económica mundial y la desmovilización de la sociedad, fomentada esta última –según explica Ortí (1989)– tanto por la bur- guesía conservadora como por las elites de los partidos y organizaciones sindicales antifranquistas que se sumaron al consenso. La desactivación de la calle favoreció la estrategia de cambio controlado y limitado a los aspectos formales de la democracia. 6. Vid., a modo ilustrativo, Viver i Pi-Sunyer (1998: 29). 7. A este respecto, las reflexiones de Queralt son absolutamente pertinentes: «como decía Heráclito no se puede entrar dos veces en el mismo río lo que, aplicado a nuestro caso, […] significa que no tiene sentido reescribir la His- toria. Pero lo que no decía Heráclito es que haya que bañarse siempre en el mismo pútrido río y que no asista el de- recho al saneamiento de tales aguas. No se trata de revisar la Historia […]. De lo que se trata es de devolver a quienes impunemente y con publicidad se les arrebató lo que hace que una persona sea persona: su dignidad» (2011: 929). Revista de Paz y Conflictos issn 1988-7221 | Vol. 9 | Nº 1 | 2016 | pp. 209-234 213 plano individual se reconoce un derecho a saber qué pasó cuyos titulares son las víctimas y sus familiares y amigos. Este derecho entraña un deber correlativo de investigar los hechos a cargo del Estado. En el plano colectivo, la verdad consiste en el derecho de la sociedad a conocer la historia para evitar su repetición. Es lo que se conoce como derecho a la memoria histórica. En contrapartida, el Estado tiene un deber de preservar esa memoria «a fin de prevenir contra las deformaciones de la historia» denominadas revisionismo y negacionismo (Joinet, 1997: §17). Las medidas que sugiere Joinet para proceder a esclarecer la verdad son dos: la crea- ción de comisiones no judiciales de investigación, más conocidas como comisiones de la verdad, y la preservación de todos aquellos archivos relacionados con las violaciones de Derechos Humanos (1997: §18). Pues bien, en España no se creó ninguna comisión de la verdad durante la Transición ni aun después. El consenso, tan alabado, que posibilitó el tránsito pacífico8 de la dicta- dura a la democracia se basó en un pacto de silencio y olvido del pasado, tanto el infame –el golpe de Estado y la dictadura– como el democrático –la República y la resistencia antifranquista–. Se pretendía evitar la apertura de viejas heridas para, de ese modo, lograr la reconciliación nacional. Semejante actitud contribuyó a difundir la tesis de la equidis- tancia entre ambos bandos, responsables por igual de crímenes terribles.9 Con la Ley de Memoria Histórica10 se perdió una buena oportunidad de avanzar en el esclarecimiento de la verdad. Pese a que entre los objetivos declarados de la norma se encuentra la recuperación de la memoria personal y familiar «de quienes padecieron per- secución o violencia, por razones políticas, ideológicas o de creencia religiosa, durante la Guerra Civil y la Dictadura» (artículo 1.1), así como, en el marco de las políticas públi- cas, fomentar «los valores y principios democráticos, facilitando el conocimiento de los hechos y circunstancias acaecidos durante la Guerra Civil y la Dictadura y asegurando la preservación de los documentos relacionados con ese período histórico y depositados en archivos públicos» (artículo 1.2), lo cierto es que la regulación es insuficiente para colmar el deber de memoria e investigación que incumbe al Estado –más aún, en ningún lugar aparecen recogidas las obligaciones del Estado, sólo se habla de derechos de las víctimas y sus familiares– y la aplicación no ha sido demasiado efectiva.11 8. A juicio de Monedero, «que la transición fue pacífica es un mito injustificable» (2013: 142), teniendo en cuenta la violencia brutal que desplegaron tanto la extrema derecha como la extrema izquierda, ETA, el GRAPO y las fuer- zas y cuerpos de seguridad del Estado. En palabras de Sánchez Cuenca, «exceptuando la transición rumana […], la española ha sido la más sangrienta en Europa» (2009: 10). Una buena descripción de tal violencia puede leerse en Sánchez Soler (2010). 9. Resultan sumamente ilustrativas las siguientes palabras de Monedero: «si […] la mejor forma de esconder un elefante en la Gran Vía es llenando la Gran Vía de elefantes, para que no hubiera culpables de la guerra era necesario que todos fueran culpables. Se sentaban las bases para entender la Guerra Civil como el resultado de un enfren- tamiento fratricida entre los españoles, un pueblo que aún no había aprendido a convivir pacíficamente. El relato era amable para los hijos de los vencedores, que ganaban en moralidad respecto de sus padres, pero seguía siendo inmoral para la consciencia de los vencidos, culpables solamente de haber intentado defender la legalidad vigente en 1936» (2013: 169). 10. Ley 52/2007, de 26 de diciembre, por la que se reconocen y amplían derechos y se establecen medidas a favor de quienes padecieron persecución o violencia durante la guerra civil y la dictadura. 11. Mucho menos desde que el Partido Popular (PP) dejó sin fondos la aplicación de la Ley de Memoria Histórica. artículos originales Payero López, Lucia. Justicia de transición en España: claves para aprobar una asignatura pendiente214 La ley contempla tres dimensiones del derecho a la verdad: la localización y exhu- mación de fosas comunes, la investigación histórica acerca de la dictadura y la gestión de los monumentos y símbolos públicos. El primer asunto se contiene en los artículos 11-14. El artículo 11.1 regula el derecho de los familiares a conocer el paradero de sus muertos en los siguientes términos: «las Administraciones Públicas, en el ejercicio de sus competencias, facilitarán a los descendientes directos de las víctimas que así lo soliciten las actividades de indagación, localización e identificación de las personas desaparecidas violentamente durante la Guerra Civil y la represión política posterior y cuyo paradero se ignore» (cursiva añadida). Esta colaboración del Estado con los particulares en la búsqueda de los cadáveres de los desaparecidos, que se iniciará siempre a instancia de parte, se queda lejos de lo que precep- túan las normas internacionales en la materia y consagra una especie de «privatización de la verdad» (Amnistía Internacional, 2006).12 Y es que el deber de recordar e investigar que corresponde al Estado no depende de que lo pidan las partes; incluso los Estados habrían de alentar a las víctimas a ejercer su derecho a la memoria (Naciones Unidas, 2005: §12). En los artículos 20-22 se establecen medidas acerca de los estudios de investigación histórica: de este modo, se «constituye el Centro Documental de la Memoria Histórica» en Salamanca (artículo 20.1), estableciéndose «el derecho de acceso a los fondos docu- mentales depositados en los archivos públicos y la obtención de las copias que se soliciten» (artículo 22.1). Particularmente importantes son las disposiciones acerca de la gestión de los monu- mentos y simbología públicas que se contienen en los artículos 15-17. El artículo 15.1 dice: «las Administraciones Públicas, en el ejercicio de sus competencias, tomarán las medidas oportunas para la retirada de escudos, insignias, placas y otros objetos o men- ciones conmemorativas de exaltación, personal o colectiva, de la sublevación militar, de la Guerra Civil y de la represión de la Dictadura». La aplicación de este precepto ha sido limitada y todavía perduran monumentos de exaltación franquista en diferentes ciudades españolas, así como calles cuyos nombres recuerdan hechos o personajes relacionados con ese pasado luctuoso. Más aún, el artícu- lo 15.2 prevé una importante limitación a la retirada de símbolos franquistas: «cuando concurran razones artísticas, arquitectónicas o artístico-religiosas protegidas por la ley». Según ha señalado Capellà, si tenemos en cuenta «que buena parte de estos símbolos fas- cistas se encuentran todavía en iglesias y fachadas de edificios públicos, esta disposición La justificación ofrecida es que «no se debe remover el pasado». Y es que incluso las labores de identificación y ex- humación de cadáveres han quedado sin financiación, pese a que cuando el PP llegó al poder en 2012 aseguró que ésta iba a ser la única acción memorialista que, no sólo mantendría el presupuesto, sino que lo vería incrementado. Como el tiempo ha demostrado, otra promesa vacua (Pérez, 2015). 12. En este sentido, y como bien señalaba Gómez Isa, «al final, parece que va a ser la sociedad civil, con la ayuda de los historiadores, quien elabore la narrativa del sufrimiento de las víctimas de la Guerra Civil y el franquismo, algo que, aunque imprescindible, resulta totalmente insuficiente. […]. La verdad por sí sola no [basta], tiene que ir acompañada de un reconocimiento público del sufrimiento. La verdad no se puede quedar en el círculo más íntimo de las víctimas, sino que tiene que ser reconocida oficial y públicamente» (2012: 179). Revista de Paz y Conflictos issn 1988-7221 | Vol. 9 | Nº 1 | 2016 | pp. 209-234 215 corre el peligro de quedar en papel mojado cuando no haya voluntad política de eliminar monumentos y simbología franquista» (2009: 244). Y eso es lo que ha ocurrido. Aun así, no siempre resulta conveniente la destrucción de todos los símbolos de la dictadura; en los casos en que exista un valor artístico o, incluso, histórico relevante (véa- se, por ejemplo, el Valle de los Caídos), conviene mantenerlo, pero dándole una nueva orientación antifascista.13 De este modo, se convierte en un lugar de memoria para que las generaciones venideras sepan y vean cuán terrible fue el régimen dictatorial: es lo que ha pasado en Argentina con la antigua Escuela de Mecánica de la Armada (ESMA), con- vertida desde 2004 en un museo para la memoria y la promoción de los Derechos Hu- manos. Esta permanencia no alcanza en ningún caso a los nombres de las calles y plazas que conmemoran personajes o hechos relacionados con el pasado funesto. Como balance general, podría decirse que en la Ley de Memoria Histórica «brillan por su ausencia medidas para tratar de garantizar el derecho individual de las víctimas y el derecho colectivo de la sociedad a conocer toda la verdad» (Gómez, 2012: 179). 2.2. Justicia El principio de justicia es un requisito básico para evitar la impunidad. La justicia im- plica un derecho de las víctimas a un proceso justo y eficaz donde, si procede, se castigue a su opresor y, correlativamente, un deber del Estado de investigar concienzudamente las violaciones de Derechos Humanos que se hayan cometido, perseguir a sus autores, juzgarlos y, finalmente, condenarlos si se demuestra su culpabilidad. En su informe, Joinet sugería la adopción de dos tipos principales de medidas a fin de implementar adecuadamente el principio de justicia. En primer lugar, la concesión a la víctima de la «posibilidad de hacer valer sus derechos beneficiándose de un recurso justo y eficaz (…) para que su opresor sea juzgado» (1997: §26). Lo ideal es que la competen- cia para juzgar recaiga sobre los tribunales nacionales y que se reserve excepcionalmente la competencia a un tribunal internacional en aquellos casos en los que los primeros no puedan llevar a cabo esa labor de manera imparcial (1997: §28). En segundo lugar, el re- lator especial recomendaba la aplicación restrictiva de ciertas reglas jurídicas para impedir que favoreciesen la impunidad de los agresores. Así, la prescripción no debe regir en los crímenes contra la humanidad ni ha de contar para la misma el período de tiempo donde no haya existido un recurso eficaz (1997: §31); no cabe amnistiar a los responsables de violaciones de Derechos Humanos «en tanto las víctimas no hayan obtenido justicia por la vía de un recurso eficaz» (1997: §32) y el derecho de reparación en ningún caso puede verse afectado por la amnistía; tampoco es posible que los autores de vulneraciones de derechos gocen de los derechos de «refugio político, asilo territorial o diplomático» (1997: §33) o se amparen en el carácter político de sus crímenes a fin de evitar la extradición 13. A ello se refería De Greiff al decir: «ciertos objetos no pueden propiamente ser removidos y algunos pueden o deben mantenerse con una necesaria contextualización y «resignificación» para perder el carácter divisorio que puedan tener y poder contribuir a la pedagogía ciudadana y la memoria. El Valle de los Caídos es un buen ejemplo de ello» (2014: §29). artículos originales Payero López, Lucia. Justicia de transición en España: claves para aprobar una asignatura pendiente216 (1997: §34); ni el principio de obediencia debida ni el arrepentimiento pueden actuar como causa de exoneración de la responsabilidad penal (1997: §36-37); la jurisdicción de los tribunales militares ha de quedar limitada a las «infracciones específicamente mili- tares cometidas por militares», excluyéndose las violaciones graves de Derechos Humanos (1997: §38); por último, los jueces nombrados de manera ilegítima deben ser destituidos, mientras que aquellos que fueron removidos del cargo durante la dictadura han de ser reintegrados a su puesto (1997: §39). De los tres aspectos que comporta la justicia de transición, el derecho a la justicia ha sido, quizá, el que ha alcanzado un menor desarrollo en España. Si no se esclareció la verdad de lo ocurrido, mucho menos iba a procederse a juzgar a los responsables. Parece que «ni siquiera durante los años previos al inicio formal de la transición, y ni aun los partidos de la extrema izquierda, demandaron abiertamente la persecución y castigo ju- dicial de los responsables de los crímenes pasados» (Chinchón, 2007: 134). Y es que «las demandas más repetidas de la oposición moderada […] fueron, además de la amnistía, la [abolición] de las jurisdicciones especiales. Todo lo relacionado con la supresión de los cuerpos represivos y la devolución del patrimonio expoliado a los particulares (por la Ley de Responsabilidades Políticas de 1939) tendió a dejarse de lado y las medidas de justicia política nunca llegaron a plantearse con la suficiente claridad» (Aguilar, 2001 :16). Las dos peticiones de la oposición democrática se cumplieron, pero en ambos casos las concesiones contenían un gusano oculto. Por lo que se refiere a la eliminación de las ju- risdicciones especiales, el Tribunal de Orden Público (TOP) desapareció en enero de 1977, pero sus magistrados no fueron depurados, sino que se integraron automáticamente en la sala de lo Penal de la Audiencia Nacional (AN), un tribunal más que cuestionable en un Estado de derecho (vid. Andrés, 2012: 169-170). Por lo que hace a la amnistía, se solicitaba para los presos políticos de la dictadura. La Ley 46/1977, de 15 de octubre, constituyó el hito fundamental en este sentido, al amnistiar «todos los actos de intencionalidad política, cualquiera que fuese su resultado, tipificados como delitos y faltas, realizados al día 15 de diciembre de 1976», así como los cometidos entre esa fecha y el 15 de junio de 1977 «cuando en la intencionalidad política se aprecie además un móvil de restablecimiento de las libertades públicas o de reivindica- ción de autonomías de los pueblos de España». Si los actos con esos fines no supusieron «violencia grave contra la vida o la integridad de las personas» la amnistía se extiende hasta el 6 de octubre de 1977 (artículo 1.1). No obstante, durante el trámite parlamentario se colaron dos cláusulas que amnistiaban también a los violadores de Derechos Humanos y que resultarían finalmente aprobadas: «están comprendidos en la amnistía […] los delitos y faltas que pudieran haber cometido las autoridades, funcionarios y agentes del orden público, con motivo u ocasión de la investigación y persecución de los actos incluidos en esta Ley, [así como] los delitos cometidos por los funcionarios y agentes del orden público contra el ejercicio de los derechos de las personas» (artículo 2 e, f ). A partir de ese momento, en las escasas ocasiones en que se intentaron investigar y juzgar los crímenes de la dictadura siempre fue alegada la Ley de Amnistía como un impe- Revista de Paz y Conflictos issn 1988-7221 | Vol. 9 | Nº 1 | 2016 | pp. 209-234 217 dimento legal absoluto.14 El argumento se resume más o menos así. Cuando se aprobó la Ley de Amnistía, el Derecho internacional de los Derechos Humanos se hallaba en paña- les, por lo que España no incumplió la obligación de investigar y perseguir las violaciones de Derechos Humanos que establecen, entre otros, el Estatuto de Roma de la Corte Penal Internacional (1998) o la Convención contra la tortura y otros tratos o penas crueles, inhumanos o degradantes (1984), puesto que tales normas no habían sido promulgadas todavía. España había ratificado sólo unos meses antes el Pacto Internacional de Derechos Civiles y Políticos (PIDCP), cuyo artículo 2.3 reconoce el derecho a un recurso efectivo a toda persona que vea vulnerados los derechos que el propio tratado contempla; y ello «aun cuando tal violación hubiera sido cometida por personas que actuaban en ejercicio de sus funciones oficiales». Autores como Ambos (2009a) y Gil (2009) consideran que, en primer lugar, no cabe una aplicación retroactiva del PIDCP, por lo que si los hechos ocurrieron con anterioridad a su ratificación –como es el caso– no habría derecho a recurso. En segundo lugar, incluso aunque se admitiese la retroactividad del PIDCP, el recurso no tendría que ser necesaria- mente de tipo penal, sino que bastaría el reconocimiento de acciones en el orden civil. A pesar de que España también incumplió sus obligaciones internacionales en este punto, como expresamente reconoce Gil (2009: 109), ello no significa que la Ley de Amnistía contradijese el Derecho internacional del momento. En tercer lugar, e incluso aunque la Ley de Amnistía fuese derogada, los crímenes habrían prescrito, por lo que tampoco sería posible su persecución penal. Esta es la opinión que siguen tanto el Tribunal Supremo (TS)15 como los dos principales partidos políticos de ámbito estatal. 14. El caso Ruano constituye uno de los pocos ejemplos en los que se llevaron ante los tribunales crímenes (asesinato y tortura) cometidos por funcionarios durante el franquismo. Enrique Ruano era un joven estudiante al que detuvo la policía en 1969 por repartir propaganda de Comisiones Obreras (CCOO). A los tres días, su cuerpo apareció muerto en el patio interior de una casa. Según la versión oficial, Ruano se tiró por la ventana intentando escapar (suicidio). Tal y como relata Aguilar, «dicha muerte no fue debidamente investigada e incluso se manipularon una serie de documentos y pruebas para intentar justificar la acción de Ruano basándose en su supuesto desequilibrio psicológico. […]. En 1992, los tres policías implicados en el caso se hallaban en activo en el cuerpo policial y nunca fueron castigados ni siquiera por negligencia en la custodia del detenido. En esta fecha, la familia decidió reabrir el caso y llevarlo a la justicia. Sin embargo, los abogados de los acusados adujeron, por un lado, que los veinte años transcurridos impedían, según la legislación en vigor, juzgar ningún delito y, por otro, que la Ley de Amnistía de 1977 se había aprobado para evitar este tipo de juicios. Al final, la justicia decidió que el delito no había prescrito, pero que la ausencia de pruebas determinantes (puesto que éstas se habían hecho desaparecer con anterioridad), obligaba a absolver a los tres policías implicados» (2001: 31-32). Es importante destacar, no obstante, la conclusión que extrae A. Gil de la decisión de la Audiencia Provincial de Madrid (Auto 19 diciembre 1995) en la que, «frente a la pretensión de la defensa y del Ministerio Fiscal de con- siderar los hechos amnistiados, admitió la tesis de la acusación particular afirmando que la aplicación de la Ley de Amnistía exigía un juicio valorativo sobre la intencionalidad política de los acusados que, por el momento, no había sido probada. [Por tanto, habría que deducir, en primer lugar], una interpretación restrictiva de la Ley del 77: donde dice que se amnistían los delitos cometidos por los funcionarios con la ocasión de la persecución de delitos políticos debe exigirse también en la comisión de dichos delitos el mismo móvil político. [En segundo lugar], la amnistía no impide la investigación y constatación de los hechos y del móvil político para los delitos de los funcionarios que no hubieran sido perseguidos con anterioridad, sino que, por el contrario, la constatación por el tribunal de estos presu- puestos es condición para su aplicación. Esta interpretación acercaría más nuestra Ley de Amnistía a un mecanismo de averiguación de la verdad y no de olvido absoluto» (2009: 86). 15. El Auto del TS de 28 de marzo de 2012, que resuelve la cuestión de competencia planteada por Garzón en el caso de las fosas del franquismo, hace referencia a todos estos asuntos. Con respecto a la irretroactividad de la aplica- artículos originales Payero López, Lucia. Justicia de transición en España: claves para aprobar una asignatura pendiente218 No obstante, existe una opinión alternativa16 que, sobre la base de los recientes desa- rrollos del Derecho internacional en materia de protección de los Derechos Humanos, y teniendo en cuenta el precedente sentado por la jurisprudencia de la Corte Interamerica- na de Derechos Humanos (CIDH), afirma la necesidad de derogar la Ley de Amnistía y perseguir los crímenes del franquismo. A ello obligan la coherencia política y la responsa- bilidad moral que, pese a lo que algunos autores parecen sugerir, no se encuentran reñidas con la corrección jurídica.17 ción de las normas penales internacionales dice: «el principio de legalidad y el de interdicción de la retroactividad de las normas sancionadoras no favorables (artículo 9.3 de la Constitución), que prohíben la aplicación retroactiva de las disposiciones sancionadoras a los hechos anteriores a su vigencia, impiden operar con la categoría «delitos contra la humanidad» para denotar jurídicamente y tratar procesalmente las acciones criminales de las que fueron víctimas las personas a las que se refieren las denuncias que motivan las actuaciones de referencia». También alude a la prescripción de los delitos: «por la fecha de iniciación de dichas causas, las acciones criminales sobre las que versan deben considerarse prescritas, a tenor de lo previsto en los artículos 131 y 132 del Código Penal. Es así, debido, de una parte, a que el delito de detención ilegal de carácter permanente sin dar razón del paradero de la víctima, presente en el Código Penal de 1928, desapareció en el de 1932, para ser reincorporado al de 1944, de modo que no estuvo vigente durante la mayor parte del tiempo en que tuvieron lugar las acciones que se trataría de perseguir. De otra, porque, como se dice en la STS 101/2012, el argumento de la permanencia del delito fundado en la hipotética subsistencia actual de situaciones de detención producidas en torno al año 1936, carece de plausi- bilidad. Y, en fin, porque, aun admitiendo razonablemente […] que, por la imposibilidad para los familiares de los afectados de instar la persecución de esos delitos durante la dictadura, hubiera que posponer el inicio del cómputo de la prescripción a la entrada en vigor de la Constitución, el 29 de diciembre de 1978, incluso en este supuesto, el plazo de 20 años habría transcurrido en todo caso». Finalmente, también menciona la vigencia de la Ley de Amnistía: «la Ley 46/1977 […] forma parte del ordenamien- to vigente. […] Porque a tenor de lo que dispone su artículo 6, la amnistía determinará en general la extinción de la responsabilidad criminal derivada de las penas impuestas o que pudieran imponerse; y porque, conforme a su artículo 9, será aplicable cualquiera que sea el estado de tramitación del proceso, no podría dejar de proyectar sus efectos sobre los hechos a que se refieren las denuncias que están en el origen de las actuaciones en las que se han suscitado las cuestiones que ahora se deciden» (FJ 2º). 16. Vid. Chinchón (2007, 2008), Queralt (2007), Estirado (2009), Sáez (2009), Garcés (2010), Paredes (2010, 2013) y Valencia (2012). 17. Los defensores de la vigencia de la Ley de Amnistía y, en consecuencia, de la imposibilidad de juzgar los crímenes de la dictadura, apelan a los valores del garantismo jurídico y del iuspositivismo legalista «para evitar resultados que político-criminalmente no consideran deseables» (Paredes, 2010). Un buen ejemplo lo encontramos en Gil: «se ha criticado a los tribunales españoles la incoherencia de perseguir crímenes cometidos en otros países desconociendo leyes de amnistía, mientras no persigue los cometidos en España amparados por una ley de amnistía. Sin embargo, en un país con división de poderes y con independencia judicial, las decisiones de los tribunales no tienen por qué ser políticamente correctas ni políticamente coherentes, sino sólo jurídicamente correctas y […] entiendo que la decisión de la Audiencia Nacional respecto de las leyes argentinas de Punto Final y Obediencia Debida es jurídi- camente correcta, como también lo es someterse a la propia ley de amnistía, que sí vincula a los jueces españoles –no a los extranjeros cuando persigan crímenes claramente tipificables como internacionales en el momento de su comisión–» (2009: 152). Sin embargo, España no coopera con los tribunales extranjeros que investigan crímenes franquistas, como quedó demostrado recientemente: cuando en Argentina se abrió un proceso judicial en cuyo marco la jueza Servini de Cubría dictó orden internacional de detención contra diecinueve altos cargos franquistas, el Ministerio del Interior denegó su extradición, alegando que los delitos habían prescrito y estaban amparados por la amnistía de 1977. Aun así, y según apunta Valencia, «la corrección jurídica no se puede separar de la coherencia política ni, sobre todo, de la responsabilidad moral, a menos que se pretenda que la función jurisdiccional consiste tan sólo en hacer dere- cho formal e impartir justicia ritual, lo cual termina por convertirse en positivismo puro y duro al servicio del orden o desorden establecido» (2012: 190). Además, los resultados que los defensores de la Ley de Amnistía pretenden evitar «resultarían compatibles (y aquí estriba la trampa, en negarlo) con el Derecho positivo, además de ser muy valiosos en términos político-criminales (reducción del nivel de impunidad, satisfacción de Derechos Humanos), en Revista de Paz y Conflictos issn 1988-7221 | Vol. 9 | Nº 1 | 2016 | pp. 209-234 219 2.3. Reparación La reparación que se concede a las víctimas de violaciones de Derechos Humanos presenta una doble dimensión: individual y colectiva. En el plano individual, la repara- ción consiste en un derecho a un recurso eficaz cuyo titular es la víctima, sus familiares directos, las personas a cargo de la víctima o quienes estuviesen estrechamente vinculados con ella. El deber de reparación a cargo del Estado incluye tres tipos de medidas: de resti- tución, de compensación o indemnización y de rehabilitación o readaptación. De acuerdo con la Resolución 60/147,18 «la restitución, siempre que sea posible, ha de devolver a la víctima a la situación anterior. […] Comprende, según corresponda, el restablecimiento de la libertad, el disfrute de los Derechos Humanos, la identidad, la vida familiar y la ciu- dadanía, el regreso a su lugar de residencia, la reintegración en su empleo y la devolución de sus bienes» (principio 19). El principio 20 dispone la indemnización «por todos los perjuicios económicamente evaluables», entre los que se cuentan el daño físico y mental, la pérdida de oportunidades, los daños materiales y pérdida de ingresos, incluido el lucro cesante, los perjuicios morales y los gastos de asistencia jurídica o de expertos, atención médica y psicológica. Por último, la rehabilitación incluirá «atención médica y psicológi- ca, así como servicios jurídicos y sociales» (principio 21). En el plano colectivo, el derecho a la reparación alude al ámbito moral (no económico) y comprende medidas de carácter simbólico relacionadas con la memoria histórica (algu- nas de ellas ya fueron mencionadas cuando se explicó el derecho a la verdad, puesto que verdad y reparación se hallan íntimamente conectadas en su dimensión colectiva): es lo que en la Resolución 60/147 se incluía bajo el concepto de satisfacción (principio 22). De este modo, el Estado se halla obligado a adoptar «medidas eficaces para conseguir que no continúen las violaciones, la verificación de los hechos y la revelación pública y completa de la verdad […], la búsqueda de las personas desaparecidas […], una declaración oficial o decisión judicial que restablezca la dignidad, la reputación y los derechos de la víctima […], una disculpa pública que incluya el reconocimiento de los hechos y la aceptación de responsabilidades, la aplicación de sanciones judiciales o administrativas a los responsables de las violaciones, conmemoraciones y homenajes a las víctimas, la inclusión de una ex- posición precisa de las violaciones ocurridas en la enseñanza de las normas internacionales de Derechos Humanos y del derecho internacional humanitario». términos meramente políticos y también en términos morales» (Paredes, 2010). En cualquier caso, «la incoherencia que […] revela en la proyección internacional de nuestro Estado […] la vocación expresada por nuestros órganos jurisdiccionales para erigirse en custodios del respeto de los Derechos Humanos por doquier, a través del empleo de la herramienta de la jurisdicción universal contemplada en el artículo 23.4 LOPJ», ha sido subsanada mediante las reformas operadas por la LO 1/2009, 3 noviembre, y la LO 1/2014, 13 marzo, que modificaron la LO 6/1985, 1 julio, del Poder Judicial, en lo relativo a la justicia universal (González, 2009: 84). Tras esta desnaturalización del instituto de la justicia universal ni se investigarán los crímenes de genocidio y de lesa humanidad ocurridos en España ni tampoco los que hayan tenido lugar en cualquier otro Estado. 18. Resolución 60/147, de la Asamblea General, que aprueba los Principios y directrices básicos sobre el derecho de las víctimas de violaciones manifiestas de las normas internacionales de Derechos Humanos y de violaciones graves del derecho internacional humanitario a interponer recursos y obtener reparaciones (16 diciembre 2005). artículos originales Payero López, Lucia. Justicia de transición en España: claves para aprobar una asignatura pendiente220 El ámbito de la reparación individual es, sin duda, el que ha alcanzado un mayor grado de desarrollo en España –más concretamente, en su faceta indemnizatoria–; aún así, ha- bría muchas cosas que mejorar de acuerdo con los estándares internacionales y siguiendo el ejemplo de otros países que también se enfrentaron a un pasado dictatorial. La repa- ración en España se ha entendido fundamentalmente en su vertiente económica, lo cual resulta insuficiente.19 Por esa razón se ha dicho que la Transición española responde a un «modelo de olvido del pasado «absoluto» con rehabilitación» de las víctimas (Chinchón, 2007: 136). Como ha señalado Sauca, hasta el 20 de noviembre de 2002 –fecha en que, por primera vez, el Congreso de los Diputados aprueba una declaración de reconocimien- to a las víctimas de la guerra y el franquismo20– «se habían producido diversos reconoci- mientos de derechos e indemnizaciones a los combatientes republicanos que en la mayoría de casos suponían la equiparación de derechos de los combatientes por la República con los de los vencedores» (2008: 75). Así, se llega a la Ley de Memoria Histórica, donde también se contienen medidas de reparación colectivo-simbólicas como parte del derecho a la memoria histórica.21 Por lo que se refiere a la reparación pecuniaria individual, la Ley de Memoria Histórica amplía los ámbitos de aplicación de algunos derechos ya existentes e introduce otros nuevos (vid. artículos 5-10, 18 y Disposiciones Adicionales 4-5 y 7). Algunos déficits de las políticas de reparación en España son los siguientes: no se ha construido ningún monumento nacional de homenaje a las víctimas y, por el contrario, subsisten numerosos símbolos de la dictadura (el Valle de los Caídos sin reorientación antifascista alguna,22 estatuas, placas conmemorativas, nombres de calles, listas de los 19. La concepción económica de la reparación no agota el concepto: vid. Sentencia de la CIDH, Caso Loayza Ta- mayo c. Perú, 27 noviembre 1998; Gómez (2006: 57); Villa Gómez (2013). 20. Debe señalarse que la declaración parlamentaria no condena el franquismo explícitamente, sino el totalitarismo y la violencia en sentido genérico, a la vez que reconoce el sufrimiento de las víctimas. Las condiciones que puso el PP para aprobar esta Proposición no de ley fueron dos: que se sacasen definitivamente del debate político esos asuntos y que se tuviese especial cuidado en no reabrir viejas heridas y rencores (Atencia Robledo, Diario de Sesiones del Congreso de los Diputados [DSCD] núm. 625, 20 noviembre 2002, p. 20517). De ahí que cuando en 2013 el grupo parlamentario de Izquierda Plural presentó una Proposición de ley en el Congreso de los Diputados para que el 18 de julio fuera declarado Día Oficial de Condena de la Dictadura Franquista, el PP utilizó su mayoría absoluta para impedir que la misma se admitiera a trámite (DSCD núm. 112, 21 mayo 2013). Por esta razón, Aguilar ase- guraba que «hoy en día, el PP no ha condenado todavía explícitamente el golpe de Estado de 1936 ni la dictadura que vino a continuación» (2007: 17). 21. Destaca, por ejemplo, el artículo 2.1, que «declara el carácter radicalmente injusto de todas las condenas, sancio- nes y cualesquiera formas de violencia personal producidas por razones políticas, ideológicas o de creencia religiosa, durante la Guerra Civil [y] […] la Dictadura». El artículo 3.1 declara la «ilegitimidad de los tribunales, jurados y cualesquiera otros órganos penales o adminis- trativos que, durante la Guerra Civil, se hubieran constituido para imponer, por motivos políticos, ideológicos o de creencia religiosa, condenas o sanciones de carácter personal, así como la de sus resoluciones»; en particular, «el Tribunal de Represión de la Masonería y el Comunismo, el Tribunal de Orden Público, […] los Tribunales de Responsabilidades Políticas y los Consejos de Guerra» (artículo 3.2), así como «las condenas y sanciones dictadas por motivos políticos, ideológicos o de creencia» por los tribunales de la dictadura (artículo 3.3). No obstante, «no se procede a la abolición de dichas instituciones en el sentido de que mantienen el estatuto de haber pertenecido al orden jurídico español. Dicho de otro modo, esta derogación no tiene un efecto ex tunc que se retrotraiga hasta el momento en que fue dictada la norma» (Sauca, 2008: 97). 22. La Ley de Memoria Histórica únicamente prohíbe que allí se realicen actos de naturaleza política o exaltadores de la Guerra Civil, sus protagonistas o el franquismo (artículo 16.2), pero respeta su condición de lugar de culto y Revista de Paz y Conflictos issn 1988-7221 | Vol. 9 | Nº 1 | 2016 | pp. 209-234 221 «caídos por Dios y por España» en iglesias y catedrales…); ni los monarcas ni ningún Presidente del Gobierno han pedido perdón «a las víctimas de la guerra o de la represión franquista en nombre del Estado» (Aguilar, 2007: 17); tampoco se ha disculpado la Iglesia católica, cómplice de los vencedores de la guerra; además, y en el plano de la reparación material, «nunca se aprobaron medidas destinadas a facilitar el retorno de decenas de mi- les de exiliados ni normas que ofrecieran reparación a las víctimas de la tortura» (2007: 22). A juicio de Chinchón, «los pasos dados por España se han alejado notablemente de la inmediatez exigida en toda reparación, al tiempo que, en líneas generales [se produce una] falta de adecuación con un concepto de víctima acorde a lo que dispone el derecho internacional […]. La inmensa mayoría de las iniciativas aprobadas no han tenido un verdadero carácter reparador, pues no se han basado en el reconocimiento de la existencia de ninguna violación previa, sino que más bien han sido configuradas como una suerte de compensación o igualación de regímenes» (2007: 183). Por último, resulta interesante señalar que el Estado español se ha volcado y no ha escatimado medios para reparar el sufrimiento de otras víctimas –paradigmáticamente, las del terrorismo (de ETA), pero también es llamativo el esfuerzo dedicado a la búsqueda del cadáver de Marta del Castillo, por ejemplo–, lo que denota un trato absolutamente discriminatorio que acrecienta la injusticia cometida por el Estado.23 De hecho, debiera ocurrir más bien al revés: el Estado tendría que ser incluso más diligente en la reparación de las víctimas cuando fue el causante del daño que si se trata de crímenes cometidos por particulares. Y es que hay una «notable diferencia entre delitos de particulares, inclu- so organizados, expresión de violencia privada, y los crímenes de derecho internacional ejecutados por el Estado, de modo sistemático, masivo y serial, que provocan masacres humanas. Es la distancia que existe entre el poder privado, al margen de la intensidad de la ofensa, y el poder estatal genocida» (Sáez, 2014: 11). 3. ¿Cómo subsanar los graves déficits de la justicia transicional en España? Las principales carencias de la justicia de transición en España se refieren a los ámbitos del derecho a la verdad y a la justicia. En lo que sigue, serán esbozadas algunas propuestas que, de aplicarse en este país, colmarían ciertas lagunas de su política transicional y lo acercarían a los estándares internacionales en materia de protección de las víctimas de vulneraciones graves de los Derechos Humanos. 3.1. Verdad El Comité de Derechos Humanos de Naciones Unidas aseguró recientemente que «aunque toma nota con satisfacción de las garantías dadas por el Estado parte [España] cementerio –prueba del enorme poder de la Iglesia en España–. 23. Vid. R. Sáez (2009: 100), Vicente (2009: 150), Arrojo (2014), Gordon (2014). artículos originales Payero López, Lucia. Justicia de transición en España: claves para aprobar una asignatura pendiente222 en el sentido de que la Ley de la Memoria Histórica prevé que se esclarezca la suerte que corrieron los desaparecidos, observa con preocupación las informaciones sobre los obstá- culos con que han tropezado las familias en sus gestiones judiciales y administrativas para obtener la exhumación de los restos y la identificación de las personas desaparecidas. El Estado parte debe […] prever la creación de una comisión de expertos independientes en- cargada de restablecer la verdad histórica sobre las violaciones de los Derechos Humanos cometidas durante la Guerra Civil y la dictadura y permitir que las familias identifiquen y exhumen los cuerpos de las víctimas y, en su caso, indemnizar» (2008: §9). Por tanto, convendría proceder a la des-privatización de la labor de búsqueda de los desaparecidos mediante la asunción de esa competencia por parte de las administraciones públicas. Asimismo sería necesaria la creación de una comisión de la verdad integrada por expertos independientes para proceder a esclarecer los hechos ocurridos durante la guerra y la dictadura posterior. Igualmente, el Estado español tendría que prestar una mayor atención a la recuperación de la memoria histórica, incluyendo la eliminación o reasigna- ción de significado a todos los símbolos de la dictadura y la reclamación del pasado repu- blicano como un referente válido para mejorar la democracia y avanzar por su senda:24 se pretende así recobrar «una memoria democrática que, frente al relato político hegemónico que ha actuado como pilar legitimador del sistema constitucional, reivindique el relato de las víctimas del franquismo y ponga en valor lo que supuso para España la Segunda República y la Constitución de 1931» (Escudero, 2013: 321). De este modo, la verdad histórica se «oficializaría», poniendo fin a la «excesiva fragmentación que caracteriza la construcción de la memoria en España» (De Greiff, 2014: §104g). 3.2. Justicia Por lo que se refiere a la efectividad del derecho a la justicia, tres grandes obstáculos impiden el procesamiento de los criminales de la dictadura: el principio de legalidad, la vigencia de la Ley de Amnistía y la prescripción de los delitos. El principio de legalidad exige que exista una ley previa (lex praevia) que tipifique los hechos. Esa ley podría hallarse en el ordenamiento internacional o nacional. Por lo que se refiere al primero, se ha sugerido que el Derecho creado por el Estatuto y el fallo del Tribunal Militar Internacional de Nüremberg adquirió alcance universal tras la Resolu- ción 95 (I),25 convirtiéndose en parte del Derecho consuetudinario internacional (Esti- rado, 2009: 118). En el artículo 6c de dicho Estatuto se dice que son crímenes contra la humanidad:26 «el asesinato, la exterminación, esclavización, deportación y otros actos 24. Y es que, paradójicamente, España es el único país de Europa donde se puede «ser demócrata sin ser antifascista» (Monedero, 2013: 246). En los Estados de nuestro entorno han desaparecido del imaginario oficial «desde el mismo momento de la Liberación, los nombres y las loas a los tiranos y a su extensísima cohorte de secuaces» (Queralt, 2011: 930). 25. Confirmación de los principios de Derecho internacional reconocidos por el Estatuto del Tribunal Militar Internacional de Nüremberg y por el fallo de este Tribunal. Resolución 95 (1), 11 diciembre 1946, de la Asamblea General de Naciones Unidas. 26. Tanto el Tribunal Militar Internacional de Nüremberg como el de Tokio tenían competencia para conocer no Revista de Paz y Conflictos issn 1988-7221 | Vol. 9 | Nº 1 | 2016 | pp. 209-234 223 inhumanos cometidos contra la población civil antes de la guerra o durante la misma [en España, diríamos: durante la Guerra Civil o después de la misma]; la persecución por motivos políticos, raciales o religiosos en ejecución de aquellos crímenes que sean com- petencia del Tribunal o en relación con los mismos, constituyan o no una vulneración de la legislación interna del país donde se perpetraron». Por tanto, se podría aplicar la calificación de delitos contra la humanidad a muchos de los cometidos por el régimen franquista de acuerdo con lo dispuesto en el artículo 6c del Estatuto citado,27 especialmente si tenemos en cuenta que el propio Tribunal Euro- peo de Derechos Humanos (TEDH) señaló que, «si bien el Tribunal de Nuremberg se estableció para enjuiciar a los principales criminales de guerra de los Países Europeos del Eje por los crímenes que habían cometido antes y durante la Segunda Guerra Mundial, […] la validez universal de los principios relativos a los crímenes se vio posteriormente confirmada por, inter alia, la Resolución 95 de la Asamblea General de las Naciones Uni- das (…) y más tarde por la Comisión de Derecho Internacional. Como consecuencia, la responsabilidad por crímenes contra la humanidad no puede verse limitada únicamente a los nacionales de ciertos países, ni exclusivamente a actos cometidos dentro del período específico de la Segunda Guerra Mundial».28 Sin embargo, algunos autores opinan que aunque el Derecho consuetudinario del mo- mento en que se dictó la Ley de Amnistía obligase a España a perseguir los delitos, ello no significa que la norma internacional fuera de directa aplicación por el Estado. «Máxime en lo que concierne a una obligación de castigar penalmente, algo que el Estado sólo puede hacer de acuerdo con su sistema jurídico interno y, en un país regido por el principio de legalidad, a partir de una Ley que defina la conducta punible y la pena aplicable a los sujetos responsables» (Tamarit, 2009: 137).29 sólo crímenes contra la humanidad, sino también crímenes contra la paz y crímenes de guerra. «Salvo los crímenes de guerra, los otros dos eran nuevas categorías de delitos que se aplicaron en contravención de los principios de legalidad y de no retroactividad pero que, desde entonces, sentaron un precedente de la lucha de la Humanidad contra la barbarie» (Fernández, 2010: 77). 27. Valencia considera que cuando se elaboró la Ley de Amnistía los crímenes del franquismo y la dictadura consti- tuían delitos graves contra el Derecho de gentes «a la luz de la codificación del derecho internacional de los conflic- tos armados, en su doble vertiente de derecho humanitario o derecho de Ginebra y derecho de la guerra o derecho de La Haya, que comienzan con la primera Convención de Ginebra de 1864 y con las trece Convenciones de la Haya de 1899 y de 1907, respectivamente. […]. Otros precedentes normativos de trascendencia [son] la declara- ción diplomática de los aliados de la Primera Guerra Mundial, en mayo de 1915, para condenar el genocidio de los armenios por los turcos otomanos como un crimen «contra las leyes de la humanidad»; el Acuerdo de Londres, en agosto de 1945, por el cual los aliados de la Segunda Guerra Mundial crearon el Tribunal Militar Internacional de Nuremberg para juzgar a los jerarcas de la dictadura nazi por crímenes contra la paz, contra las leyes y costumbres de la guerra y contra las leyes de la humanidad; la Convención contra el Genocidio, de diciembre de 1948, que cons- tituye el instrumento fundacional del Derecho penal internacional; y la decisión de la Comisión de Derecho Inter- nacional, en julio de 1950, que codifica como nuevas normas consuetudinarias los Principios de Nuremberg que la Asamblea General de las Naciones Unidas ya había sancionado como tales en diciembre de 1946» (2012: 196-197). 28. Decisión del TEDH, caso Kolk y Kislyiy c. Estonia, 17 enero 2006. 29. En opinión de Ambos, «la persecución jurídico internacional de los crímenes fracasa por lo general –también en el caso español […]– por su falta de redacción típica en la fecha de los hechos y la persecución nacional lo hace por su prescripción» (2009b: 14). Más aún, con relación a la persecución internacional asegura que «es controvertido en qué medida tal deber [de perseguir los crímenes internacionales] puede derivarse del derecho consuetudinario internacional (artículo 38 (b) Estatuto de la CIJ) o de los principios generales del derecho (artículo 38 (c) Estatuto artículos originales Payero López, Lucia. Justicia de transición en España: claves para aprobar una asignatura pendiente224 No obstante, otro sector de la doctrina defiende que para los crímenes de lesa huma- nidad no rige este principio del Derecho penal tradicional con el fin de evitar la impu- nidad. Por ejemplo, el juez Zupančič aseguró que el artículo 7.2 del Convenio Europeo de Derechos Humanos (CEDH) representa una «excepción al principio nullum crimen, nulla poena, sine lege praevia». Y es que si el principio de legalidad se interpreta normal- mente en un sentido restrictivo del poder estatal de castigar, «en este caso […] tiene el efecto inverso. Impide que los demandantes se beneficien de su propia interpretación del derecho». Y continúa: «es fácil imaginar un caso similar en el que los demandantes fueran altos magistrados de la RDA que hubiesen participado en la creación de la «práctica» ju- dicial […] de la impunidad. ¿Diríamos entonces que este «elemento de la interpretación judicial» (ver el apartado 82 de la sentencia) equivale a la «ley que define el delito»?».30 Refiriéndose a las Leyes de Punto Final y Obediencia Debida argentinas (leyes de am- nistía similares a la española), el Instituto Max-Planck decía: «las citadas leyes especiales son ilegales desde el punto de vista del Derecho internacional público […]. [No] se opone a esta conclusión la prohibición de retroactividad (nullum crimen sine lege praevia), sin per- juicio de que Argentina firmó los convenios respectivos de Derechos Humanos después de la perpetración de los delitos. A nivel del Derecho Internacional Público Penal este principio ya no requiere de principios legales escritos para fundamentar una penalidad, sino que –desde la jurisprudencia de Nüremberg– son suficientes los principios no escri- tos pero reconocidos por el Derecho Consuetudinario. Basta la penalidad en el momento de perpetración according to the general principles of law recognized by the community of nations (comp. Art. 15 inc. 2 PIDCP). Esta disposición quiere evitar la impunidad de gra- ves violaciones a los Derechos Humanos y/o a delitos internacionales» (1998: 284-285). Incluso el Juzgado de Instrucción nº 2 de la AN31 interpretó de este modo el principio de legalidad: «el principio de legalidad aplicable a los delitos internacionales tales como los crímenes contra la humanidad no es el interno, sino el internacional, contenido en el artículo 15 del PIDCP de 1966 […]. El CP vigente puede aplicarse retrospectivamente a conductas anteriores que ya eran criminales en el momento de cometerse con arreglo a la legalidad penal internacional; es decir, eran criminales porque estaban prohibidas en el Derecho consuetudinario internacional en esa época, aunque aún no hubieran sido tipi- ficadas en el CP español. La legalidad penal internacional debe establecerse atendiendo tanto al Derecho convencional escrito, interno e internacional, como al Derecho consue- de la CIJ). En cuanto al primero, es difícil aducir una práctica de los Estados a este efecto y el recurso a los últimos es pasible de crítica, dado que aparentemente quiere superar la falta de una práctica de los Estados o incluso una práctica contraria simplemente ignorándola» (2009b: 37). Con respecto a la existencia de una norma de ius cogens consuetudinaria anterior a 1977 que obligase a España a perseguir los crímenes de la dictadura, A. Gil todavía es más restrictiva, puesto que entiende que no se daría nin- guno de los elementos de la costumbre internacional: ni opinio iuris ni práctica consistente de los Estados (2009: 109). Igualmente, Tamarit considera que «la existencia de una costumbre internacional que impusiera a los Estados el deber de perseguir penalmente las violaciones de los Derechos Humanos era dudosa en el momento en que fue dictada la Ley de amnistía» (2009: 137). 30. Voto concurrente a la Sentencia del TEDH, caso Streletz, Kessler y Krenz c. Alemania, 22 marzo 2001. 31. Auto que declara la admisión a trámite de la querella formulada en el caso de las víctimas españolas de los cam- pos nacionalsocialistas (Diligencias Previas 211/08 L, 17 julio 2008). Revista de Paz y Conflictos issn 1988-7221 | Vol. 9 | Nº 1 | 2016 | pp. 209-234 225 tudinario o los principios generales de las naciones civilizadas». En este punto, ni siquiera la exégesis dada al principio de legalidad por parte de los tribunales españoles es unánime, puesto que el TS sigue otra orientación.32 En cualquier caso, si no es posible la aplicación directa de las normas consuetudinarias de Derecho internacional, una segunda opción consistiría en acudir al Derecho interna- cional convencional (García, 2013: 143-144), que sí cumpliría los requisitos de lex scripta y stricta. En este sentido, es necesario referirse al PIDCP, de obligado cumplimiento para nuestro país desde el 27 de abril de 1977. Más aún, España no expresó ninguna reserva a la hora de firmar este tratado. Su artículo 2.3 dice: «cada uno de los Estados Partes en el presente Pacto se compromete a garantizar que toda persona cuyos derechos o liber- tades reconocidos en el presente Pacto hayan sido violados podrá interponer un recurso efectivo, aun cuando tal violación hubiera sido cometida por personas que actuaban en ejercicio de sus funciones oficiales».33 Se ha objetado que el PIDCP no resulta aplicable a actos cometidos con anterioridad a su entrada en vigor (artículo 15.1), como son todos los ocurridos en España. Ahora bien, existe una excepción a la prohibición general de retroactividad: «nada de lo dispuesto en este artículo se opondrá al juicio ni a la condena de una persona por actos u omisiones que, en el momento de cometerse, fueran delictivos según los principios generales del derecho reconocidos por la comunidad internacional» (artículo 15.2). La pregunta clave es: los delitos cometidos durante la Guerra Civil y la dictadura, ¿se podían considerar incluidos dentro de esos «principios generales del derecho reconocidos por la comunidad internacional» en el momento en que se perpetraron? Hay buenas razones para pensar que sí. Y no ofrezco una rotunda respuesta afirmativa porque hablar de principios, particularmente en el ámbito internacional y, más concretamente, en esa época en que la protección internacional de los Derechos Humanos se hallaba en fase de gestación resulta tremendamente vago. Ahora bien –y con esto entro en el ámbito del Derecho interno, el tercero donde se puede buscar la existencia de una ley previa–, en el momento de comisión de los hechos tanto el homicidio, como la violación, las lesiones corporales o la detención ilegal se halla- ban tipificadas como delitos en el Código Penal (el de 1932 y el de 1944). Por tanto, qui- 32. La STS 101/2012, 27 febrero (caso de las fosas del franquismo), considera que el principio de legalidad exige la existencia de lex praevia (anterior a la comisión de los hechos), lex stricta (tipificada en una norma de rango le- gal), lex certa (de forma clara) y lex scripta (por escrito). Así, «en orden a la aplicación del Derecho Internacional Penal «es necesaria una precisa transposición operada según el derecho interno, al menos en aquellos sistemas que, como el español, no contemplan la eficacia directa de las normas internacionales […]. El Derecho Internacional consuetudinario no es apto según nuestras perspectivas jurídicas para crear tipos penales completos que resulten directamente aplicables por los tribunales españoles» […]. La vigencia en nuestro ordenamiento del principio de le- galidad exige que el derecho internacional sea incorporado a nuestro ordenamiento interno en la forma dispuesta en la Constitución y con los efectos dispuestos en la misma. No es posible –por más que sea sostenida por algún sector doctrinal– que las exigencias del principio de tipicidad se rellenen con la previsión contenida en el Derecho penal internacional consuetudinario, si el derecho interno no contempla esa tipicidad. Si lo hiciera con posterioridad, esa tipificación puede ser aplicada, pero siempre a partir de su publicación» (FJ 3º). 33. Entre esos derechos y libertades se encuentran la vida (artículo 6), la prohibición de la tortura (artículo 7), del trabajo forzoso (artículo 8) y de la detención ilegal (artículo 9), así como la libertad de pensamiento, conciencia y religión (artículo 18), todos ellos objeto de vulneración masiva durante la dictadura franquista. artículos originales Payero López, Lucia. Justicia de transición en España: claves para aprobar una asignatura pendiente226 zá en España se podría acudir al Derecho interno que estaba vigente cuando ocurrieron los crímenes para enjuiciarlos (Paredes, 2010). Como en el resto de Estados de nuestro entorno también se tipificaban tales conductas como delictivas, se puede entender que se daba un consenso entre las «naciones civilizadas» (artículo 7.2 CEDH) acerca de la nece- sidad de sancionarlas, por lo que se cumpliría el requisito establecido en el PIDCP para su aplicación retroactiva: que los actos «fueran delictivos según los principios generales del derecho reconocidos por la comunidad internacional». El segundo impedimento frente a la pretensión de juzgar los crímenes del franquismo es la vigencia de la Ley de Amnistía. Aquí se vuelve necesario precisar algunos extremos. En primer lugar, y como ya fue mencionado, la Ley de Amnistía se aprobó unos meses des- pués de que España ratificase el PIDCP, motivo por el cual algunos autores han sugerido que la primera vulneró el Derecho internacional aplicable en nuestro país. Las relaciones entre el Derecho internacional y el Derecho interno, para el caso de un tratado anterior a una ley nacional –por ejemplo, el PIDCP y la Ley de Amnistía española–, se explican acudiendo al principio de aplicabilidad preferente. De acuerdo con el artículo 27 del Convenio de Viena sobre Derecho de los Tratados de 1969 (CVDT), «una parte no podrá invocar las disposiciones de su Derecho interno como justificación del incumplimiento de un tratado». Y es que, en el fondo, obrar en sentido contrario significaría quebrantar el propio ordenamiento nacional, puesto que la violación del Derecho internacional es, en sí misma, una transgresión del primero (Requejo, 1992: 62-63). Por tanto, la Ley de Amnistía se aprobó en contravención de la normativa internacional ratificada por España en aquel momento; esgrimir su vigencia como argumento para eximir al Estado de su de- ber de perseguir los crímenes de Derecho internacional cometidos durante el franquismo (vid., Gil, 2009: 152) supone conculcar el artículo 27 del CVDT citado.34 Un segundo punto a destacar es que desde el momento en que se aprueba la Cons- titución los jueces deben tener presente esta norma siempre que apliquen Derecho –sea éste preconstitucional o posterior a la Constitución–, así como los valores superiores que propugna (entre ellos, la justicia).35 En este sentido, nuestra Constitución es incompatible 34. Más aún, como indica Paredes, «sin necesidad de acudir al efecto derogatorio del Derecho internacional de los Derechos Humanos sobre la legislación ordinaria, simplemente mediante la realización de una interpretación sistemática y valorativamente coherente de la Ley, habría que concluir que ciertos actos no fueron amnistiados: en concreto, aquellos que han sido declarados no susceptibles de amnistía ni de prescripción por la interpretación consolidada del Derecho internacional de los Derechos Humanos. Por lo demás, […] aun si tal interpretación no resultase posible (que lo es), la conclusión que debería extraerse no es que la Ley 46/1977 –interpretada como causa de extinción de la responsabilidad penal– se impone sobre el Derecho internacional de los Derechos Humanos, sino justamente la contraria: que se trata de una ley inválida ya ab initio (o, cuando menos, posteriormente derogada), por contradecir normas de rango superior» (2013: 39). 35. Como señaló el juez Levits, en su voto concurrente a la Sentencia del TEDH, caso Streletz, Kessler y Krenz c. Alemania, ante la cuestión de si «después de un cambio de sistema político (…) es legítimo aplicar el «viejo» derecho establecido por el régimen no democrático anterior de acuerdo con los métodos de interpretación y aplicación del derecho inherentes al nuevo orden político democrático», [la única respuesta posible es sí]. «Los Estados democrá- ticos sólo pueden permitir a sus instituciones que apliquen el derecho –incluido el derecho anterior dictado por un gobierno pre-democrático– de una manera inherente al orden político democrático […]. El recurso a cualquier otro método de aplicación del derecho (que implica alcanzar resultados diferentes a partir de los mismos textos jurídicos) atentaría contra el núcleo mismo del orden público de un Estado democrático. Los mismos principios resultan igualmente aplicables respecto a la interpretación y aplicación de las normas del Derecho internacional, Revista de Paz y Conflictos issn 1988-7221 | Vol. 9 | Nº 1 | 2016 | pp. 209-234 227 con una ley que ampara la impunidad de asesinos, torturadores, secuestradores y viola- dores a gran escala de los Derechos Humanos, por lo que tanto el artículo 2 e) y f ) de la Ley de Amnistía como las sentencias dictadas por los tribunales franquistas deberían ser suprimidas, expulsadas del ordenamiento jurídico, por injustas.36 Al igual que se hizo en otros países.37 Otra posibilidad sería declarar la «inconstitucionalidad sobrevenida […] por vulne- ración del artículo 15 (derecho a la vida e integridad física y prohibición de la tortura y tratos inhumanos y degradantes)», en relación con el artículo 10.2 («interpretación de los derechos conforme a las declaraciones internacionales») (Tamarit, 2010: 68). Ello con- duciría a una segunda inconstitucionalidad sobrevenida, puesto que la Ley de Amnistía es contraria al Derecho internacional de los Derechos Humanos y los tratados en esta materia no sólo sientan la pauta hermenéutica de los derechos fundamentales, sino que son parte del ordenamiento jurídico español si han sido ratificados por España –artículo 96.1 de la Constitución– (Estirado, 2009: 123).38 En tercer lugar, el TEDH, cuya interpretación del CEDH vincula a España,39 ha afirmado que los delitos contemplados en el artículo 7.2 del CEDH –delitos con arre- glo a los principios generales del Derecho reconocido por las naciones civilizadas– son incompatibles con la amnistía.40 En definitiva, «los crímenes del franquismo no podían ser amnistiados entonces y no pueden ser amnistiados ahora porque eran delitos graves contra el Derecho de gentes y lo siguen siendo en la actualidad» (Valencia, 2012: 196).41 como el PIDCP». 36. La necesidad de anular «las resoluciones de los tribunales de excepción que instituyó el estado fascista» deriva de la siguiente asunción: «el aparato institucional franquista fue un estado ilegal, un espacio de no derecho, porque se sustentaba sobre la violación sistemática de los derechos y libertades y conculcaba la legalidad internacional, el orden jurídico universal [basado] en los Derechos Humanos indisponibles» (Sáez, 2009: 85-86). 37. En palabras de Queralt, «ampararse en la irretroactividad de la Constitución es una añagaza. Si fuera verdad esa mentira, en los matrimonios celebrados antes de la Carta Magna seguiría mandando el marido. Afirmar que anular una sentencia del TOP o de un consejo de guerra es atentar contra la seguridad jurídica resulta grotesco […]; también supone afirmar la supraconstitucionalidad de la seguridad jurídica por encima del valor superior de la Constitución que es la Justicia» (2007). 38. A juicio de Estirado, «en la medida en que la Ley de Amnistía, en cuanto impide la persecución penal de los citados crímenes de lesa humanidad, es contraria al Derecho Penal Internacional y a principios esenciales del mis- mo, con fuerza de ius cogens, y que tal Derecho Internacional ha sido recogido por nuestra Constitución de 1978 a través de los artículos 10 y 96, debe entenderse derogada esta Ley por la Constitución en este concreto ámbito, sin necesidad de plantearse la correspondiente cuestión de inconstitucionalidad» (2009: 123). 39. Vid. artículo 10.2 de la Constitución y STC 245/1991, 16 diciembre (FJ 3º). 40. Decisión del TEDH sobre la admisibilidad de la demanda nº 13113/03 presentada por Ely Ould Dah c. Fran- cia, 17 marzo 2009. Naciones Unidas se muestra igualmente contraria a las amnistías. Vid. Resolución 3074 (XVIII), 3 diciembre 1973, de la Asamblea General de Naciones Unidas que establece Principios de cooperación internacional en la identifi- cación, detención, extradición y castigo de los culpables de crímenes de guerra o de crímenes de lesa humanidad (apartado 8). También la Declaración y Programa de Acción de Viena aprobados por la Conferencia Mundial de Derechos Humanos el 25 de junio de 1993. El Comité de Derechos Humanos de Naciones Unidas recomienda asimismo la derogación de la Ley de Amnistía de 1977 (2008). 41. Más aún, en España no se cumplían las circunstancias en las que, a juicio de algunos autores, cabe justificar una amnistía: el peligro de que, al tratar de satisfacer el derecho a la justicia de las víctimas, se pongan en peligro la paz y el orden democrático. Puede ser discutible hasta qué punto las elites del régimen franquista hubieran aceptado artículos originales Payero López, Lucia. Justicia de transición en España: claves para aprobar una asignatura pendiente228 Por lo que atañe a la prescripción de los crímenes, hay quien ha apuntado que aun cuando se interpretase el principio de legalidad como aquí se postula y se derogase la Ley de Amnistía, tampoco sería posible juzgar a los criminales de la dictadura que todavía se encuentren con vida porque sus delitos habrían prescrito. No obstante, el TEDH señala que la imprescriptibilidad de los crímenes contra la humanidad, independientemente de la fecha de su comisión, ya fue consagrada por el Estatuto del Tribunal de Nüremberg.42 Igualmente, el Comité de Derechos Humanos de Naciones Unidas «recuerda que los delitos de lesa humanidad son imprescriptibles. [Por esa razón], el Estado parte debe […] tomar las medidas legislativas necesarias para garantizar el reconocimiento de la imprescriptibilidad de los crímenes de lesa humanidad por los tribunales nacionales» (2008). El Código Penal español también recoge el carácter imprescriptible de los delitos de lesa humanidad (artículo 131.4). Es más, se viene en- tendiendo que la imprescriptibilidad de los crímenes contra la humanidad era una regla consuetudinaria con carácter previo a su codificación internacional o interna.43 De cualquier modo, los plazos de prescripción no han de contar durante el tiempo en que no existió el derecho a un recurso efectivo. Para el caso paradigmático de las des- apariciones forzadas, el Derecho internacional considera que se trata de un hecho ilícito de carácter continuado. Así, de acuerdo con el artículo 17.1 de la Declaración sobre la protección de todas las personas contra las desapariciones forzadas,44 «todo acto de des- aparición forzada será considerado delito permanente mientras sus autores continúen ocultando la suerte y el paradero de la persona desaparecida y mientras no se hayan es- clarecido los hechos», aunque la persona desaparecida haya muerto.45 Igualmente, el artí- una Transición que no les garantizase la inmunidad, pero de lo que no hay duda es de que en España la amnistía no reunió las condiciones de legitimidad exigidas: ni hubo arrepentimiento (admisión de la culpa, petición pública de perdón, demostración de remordimiento, propósito de enmienda, reconocimiento de las víctimas, entrega de infor- mación, participación en programas de reeducación) ni esclarecimiento de la verdad (por ejemplo, con la creación de Comisiones de la Verdad) ni reparación del daño. Por tanto, la española no sería una amnistía condicionada, sino una amnistía general o incondicionada –blanket amnesty– (Dorado, 2013: 88-98). 42. Decisiones del TEDH, casos Papon c. Francia, 11 octubre 2005, y Touvier c. Francia, 13 enero 1997. 43. Tamarit llama la atención sobre el instituto de la prescripción: «la opinión dominante en la doctrina y en la jurisprudencia entiende que es una institución de derecho material no susceptible de aplicación retroactiva. La pres- cripción de un delito supone un límite al ejercicio de la potestad punitiva estatal y una vez producida la misma con arreglo a la ley vigente existe una expectativa legítima de no ser perseguido penalmente que no puede ser defraudada mediante una ley posterior que establezca el carácter imprescriptible del delito, como ha sucedido respecto a los delitos de lesa humanidad» (2009: 137). Por su parte, Muñoz Conde estima que «razones de seguridad jurídica avalan […] la prohibición de retroactividad de nuevos plazos de prescripción que alarguen los que regían en el momento en que se cometieron los hechos, para poder juzgar esos hechos conforme a los nuevos plazos» (2011: 857). Ahora bien, este penalista contempla la posi- bilidad de entender interrumpido el plazo de prescripción, «bien porque se hayan cometido nuevos delitos (como puede ser el caso de la Dictadura franquista que duró casi cuarenta años), bien porque se hayan querido oponer obstáculos a su persecución otorgándose los propios criminales antes del transcurso de los plazos de prescripción Leyes de Punto final o de Autoamnistía, o se hayan aprobado éstas ya en la nueva etapa democrática por debilidad de los nuevos regímenes democráticos» (2011: 859). 44. Aprobada por la Resolución 47/133, 18 diciembre 1992, de la Asamblea General de Naciones Unidas. 45. Este es el argumento que sostiene el Ministerio Fiscal en España: la desaparición forzada finalizó hace mucho tiempo porque se sabe que las víctimas fueron ejecutadas; de este modo, se trataría de un asesinato y estaría pres- crito. Sin embargo, como subraya Vicente, «esta interpretación hace total abstracción del artículo 17 de la Declara- Revista de Paz y Conflictos issn 1988-7221 | Vol. 9 | Nº 1 | 2016 | pp. 209-234 229 culo 5 de la Convención internacional para la protección de todas las personas contra las desapariciones forzadas dispone: «la práctica generalizada o sistemática de la desaparición forzada constituye un crimen de lesa humanidad tal como está definido en el Derecho in- ternacional aplicable». En su artículo 8 añade: «sin perjuicio de lo dispuesto en el artículo 5, cada Estado parte que aplique un régimen de prescripción a la desaparición forzada tomará las medidas necesarias para que el plazo de prescripción de la acción penal […] se cuente a partir del momento en que cesa la desaparición forzada, habida cuenta del carácter continuo de este delito». Por tanto, coincido con R. Sáez en que tales crímenes «no puede considerarse que han prescrito, cuando menos de manera concluyente como se pretende y sin haber procedido a la investigación. Porque, según nuestro código penal, en el caso de delitos permanentes los términos de la prescripción no se computarán hasta que se elimine la situación antijurídica (artículo 132.1). [De ahí que] pudiera sostenerse con razón que la legislación aplicable al delito permanente es la vigente en el momento del descubrimiento del desaparecido» (2009: 101-102). En este sentido, nuestro TS yerra al negar cualquier posibilidad de investigar judi- cialmente y, en su caso, procesar a los criminales de la dictadura que aún se hallen vivos. Una interpretación flexible tanto del principio de legalidad como del instituto de la pres- cripción y de la constitucionalidad de la Ley de Amnistía permitiría cierto ámbito de maniobra a los jueces. Mi propuesta no socava el principio de intervención mínima del Derecho penal ni cae en la ingenua tentación de pretender solucionar todos los problemas que aquejan a una sociedad acudiendo a la vía penal; tampoco desnaturaliza el Estado de derecho con- virtiéndolo en un Estado de desecho por atentar contra principios garantistas básicos. Las instituciones que sugiero interpretar de forma flexible (principio de legalidad, irretroac- tividad de la ley penal desfavorable, prescripción de los delitos), en el supuesto único y exclusivo de juzgar crímenes contra la humanidad cometidos por dictadura, se crearon para proteger al ciudadano frente al poder estatal que, si no se limita, tiende siempre al totalitarismo. Pero no buscaban beneficiar a quienes, prevaliéndose de la legitimidad y fuerza que otorga el Estado, vulnerasen los derechos fundamentales de los ciudadanos de forma masiva, aprovechándose luego de las garantías que ellos ignoraron para librarse de cualquier castigo. En este sentido, creo que es importante distinguir entre el crimen de Estado y el delito cometido por particulares –incluso aunque se trate de bandas organi- zadas–: por muy grave que sea el último, no se puede comparar con el carácter masivo, serial y sistemático del primero. Además de la presunción de moralidad que acompaña a la ley –y, en general, a toda actuación estatal–, un Estado que delinque se convierte en ción de 1992. El hecho de que las «detenciones ilegales sin dar razón del paradero de la víctima» concluyeran con la ejecución de la persona detenida, por mucho que fuera un hecho notorio y público, no cambia en absoluto la calificación del delito como un acto de desaparición forzada, que constituye un delito permanente, lo que significa que la violación se prolonga en el tiempo y no concluye hasta que sea determinado el paradero de las personas desaparecidas o debidamente localizados o identificados los restos. […]. Y, en todo caso, no se trataría de un delito común […], sino uno (asesinato) constitutivo de un crimen contra la humanidad. Es adicionalmente abusivo afir- mar prescripción o limitaciones de orden temporal cuando las víctimas han sido privadas de recursos efectivos por décadas, condición que en el caso de España ha sido el auténtico hecho público y notorio» (2009: 160). artículos originales Payero López, Lucia. Justicia de transición en España: claves para aprobar una asignatura pendiente230 juez y parte: quienes atentaron gravemente contra los Derechos Humanos se hallan luego en la posición de dictar normas que les exoneren de responsabilidad (amnistías). De este modo, ni los crímenes fueron perseguidos durante el régimen totalitario ni tampoco lo serán una vez instaurada la democracia. Esta situación no acaece en los casos de violencia privada, donde, mientras no prescriba el delito, el autor se halla siempre en la posición de ser capturado y procesado. Más aún, para los crímenes contra la humanidad no resultan aplicables varias de las justificaciones tradicionales del instituto de la prescripción46. En primer lugar, no desaparece la necesidad de la pena, ni desde un punto de vista preventivo general (porque se oscurezca o apague el recuerdo del delito y el sentimiento de alarma que en su día pudo producir o bien porque se entienda que el tiempo transcurrido ocul- tándose de la Justicia y con la amenaza pendiente de la pena sea ya suficiente castigo) ni, incluso, preventivo especial (porque el delincuente no haya reincidido, demostrando así una verdadera reinserción social). Por lo que hace al fundamento procesal (el aumento de las dificultades de prueba por el paso del tiempo, que se traduce en una afectación negativa del derecho de defensa y de la presunción de inocencia), en los delitos privados, al ser la dilación culpa del aparato represivo estatal, es lógico que redunde en provecho del reo; pero no ocurre eso en este supuesto, donde los que detentaban el poder para per- seguir los delitos no lo ejercieron porque ello significaba actuar contra sí mismos: parece lógico que los responsables de la demora no puedan prevalerse de beneficios adicionales (prescripción) a los que reporta el no haber sido juzgados durante la dictadura. Quisiera concluir con la siguiente reflexión: «ninguna sociedad se rompe porque se aplique la justicia […]. Una sociedad democrática mucho menos».47 Pues bien, la so- ciedad española no escapa a esa consideración. Y, en materia transicional, aquí no se ha aplicado la justicia. 4. Referencias bibliográficas Aguilar, Paloma (2001) Justicia, política y memoria: los legados del franquismo en la Transición española, Working paper, nº 163. Aguilar, Paloma (2007) La justicia transicional en los casos español, argentino y chi- leno», Comunicación presentada a la Conferencia Internacional «Paz y Justicia – Ele- mentos Conformadores del Futuro» celebrada en Nüremberg (25-27 junio), pp. 1-34. Ambos, Kai (2009a) El marco jurídico de la justicia de transición, en Ambos, Kay; Malarino, Ezequiel y Elsner, Gisela (eds.) Justicia de transición. Informes de Amé- rica Latina, Alemania, Italia y España, Berlín, Fundación Konrad-Adanauer, pp. 23-129. 46. Sigo, en lo esencial, a Mir (2011: 773). 47. Baltasar Garzón, Escuchando al juez Garzón, España, 2011, 87 min., Dir. I. Coixet. Curriculum vitae Revista de Paz y Conflictos issn 1988-7221 | Vol. 9 | Nº 1 | 2016 | pp. 209-234 231 Ambos, Kai (2009b) Prólogo, en Gil, Alicia, La justicia de transición en España. De la amnistía a la memoria histórica, Barcelona, Atelier, pp. 11-20. Amnistía Internacional (2006) Víctimas de la Guerra Civil y el régimen franquista: el desastre de los archivos, la privatización de la verdad, Informe de 30 de marzo. Andrés Ibáñez, Perfecto (2012) Casos Garzón: necesario distinguir», Isonomía, núm. 37, pp. 169-200. Arrojo, Emilio (2014) El franquismo os sienta muy bien, Público, 16 septiembre. En: . [Consultado el 4 diciembre 2015] Capellà, Margalida (2009) Represión política y Derecho internacional: una perspec- tiva comparada (1936-2006), en Capellà, Margalida y Ginard, David (coords.) Represión política, justicia y reparación. La memoria histórica en perspectiva jurídica (1936-2008), Palma de Mallorca, Edicions Documenta Balear, pp. 161-254. Chinchón, Javier (2007) El viaje a ninguna parte: memoria, leyes, historia y olvido sobre la Guerra Civil y el pasado autoritario en España. Un examen desde el Dere- cho internacional, Revista IIDH, nº 45, pp. 119-233. Chinchón, Javier (2008) Transición española y justicia transicional: ¿qué papel juega el ordenamiento jurídico internacional en un proceso de transición? A propósito de la coherencia, buena fe y otros principios de Derecho internacional postergados en la transición política de España, Entelequia, nº 7, pp. 331-354. Dorado Porras, Javier (2013) Justicia transicional, persecución penal y amnistías, De- rechos y Libertades, nº 28, pp. 81-114. Elster, Jon (2006) Rendición de cuentas. La justicia transicional en perspectiva histórica, Buenos Aires, Katz. Escudero, Rafael (2013) Jaque a la Transición: análisis del proceso de recuperación de la memoria histórica, Anuario de Filosofía del Derecho, nº 29, pp. 319-340. Estirado, César (2009) Perseguibilidad penal de los crímenes del franquismo. Aplica- ción del Derecho penal internacional al caso español. Antecedentes judiciales en España y en el extranjero, en VV.AA. Memoria histórica: ¿se puede juzgar la historia?, Madrid, Fundación Antonio Carretero, pp. 113-128. Fernández Liesa, Carlos R. (2010) La aplicabilidad de la costumbre internacional en el Derecho penal español, en Tamarit, Josep (coord.) Justicia de transición, justicia penal internacional y justicia universal, Barcelona, Atelier, pp. 73-90. Garcés, Joan E. (2010) Los crímenes de lesa humanidad en España ante el Tribunal Supremo, en Tamarit, Josep (coord.) Justicia de transición, justicia penal internacio- nal y justicia universal, Barcelona, Atelier, pp. 175-190. García Sáez, José Antonio (2013) Memoria histórica y aplicación retroactiva de la sanción penal. Algunos fundamentos desde el pacifismo jurídico de Hans Kelsen, Eunomía. Revista en Cultura de la Legalidad, nº 4, pp. 139-153. Gil, Alicia (2009) La justicia de transición en España. De la amnistía a la memoria his- tórica, Barcelona, Atelier. http://blogs.publico.es/dominiopublico/11051/el-franquismo-os-sienta-muy-bien/ http://blogs.publico.es/dominiopublico/11051/el-franquismo-os-sienta-muy-bien/ artículos originales Payero López, Lucia. Justicia de transición en España: claves para aprobar una asignatura pendiente232 Gómez Isa, Felipe (2006) El derecho de las víctimas a la reparación por violaciones graves y sistemáticas de los Derechos Humanos, en Gómez Isa, Felipe (dir.) El de- recho a la memoria, Zarautz, Alberdania, pp. 23-76. Gómez Isa, Felipe (2012) Retos de la justicia transicional en contextos no transiciona- les: el caso español, en Ripol, Santiago y Villán, Carlos (eds.) Justicia de transición: el caso de España, Barcelona, Institut Català Internacional per la Pau, pp. 172-184. González Vega, Javier (2009) Memoria histórica vs. impunidad: las obligaciones im- puestas por el Derecho internacional, en VV.AA., Memoria histórica: ¿se puede juz- gar la historia? Madrid, Fundación Antonio Carretero, pp. 67-84. Gordon, Jordi (2014) La gran vergüenza de la democracia española, Público, 10 di- ciembre. http://blogs.publico.es/dominiopublico/11965/la-gran-verguenza-de-la- democracia-espanola/. [Consultado el 5 diciembre 2015]. Greiff, Pablo de (2014) Informe del Relator Especial sobre la promoción de la verdad, la justicia, la reparación y las garantías de no repetición, (UN Doc A/HCR/27/56/ Add.1). Instituto Max-Planck (1998) Dictamen producido por el Instituto Max-Planck para el Derecho penal extranjero e internacional en Friburgo de Brisgonia, Alemania, acerca del siguiente problema jurídico, en Plataforma Argentina Contra la Impu- nidad (eds.) Contra la impunidad. En defensa de los Derechos Humanos, Barcelona, Icaria, pp. 266-290. Joinet, Louis (1997) Informe final revisado acerca de la impunidad de los autores de violaciones de los Derechos Humanos (civiles y políticos) preparado por el Sr. L. Joinet de conformidad con la Resolución 1996/119 de la Subcomisión, (UN Doc E/CN.4/Sub.2/1997/20/Rev.1). Mir Puig, Santiago (2011) Derecho penal: parte general, Barcelona, Reppertor. Monedero, Juan Carlos (2013) La Transición contada a nuestros padres. Nocturno de la democracia española, Madrid, Los Libros de la Catarata. Muñoz Conde, Francisco José (2011) El Derecho penal en tiempos de cólera, en Nuñez, Paz, Miguel Ángel (ed.) Un Derecho penal comprometido. Libro homenaje al Prof. Dr. Gerardo Landrove Díaz, Valencia, Tirant lo Blanch, pp. 851-883. Naciones Unidas (2004) El Estado de derecho y la justicia de transición en las socie- dades que sufren o han sufrido conflictos, Informe del Secretario General (UN Doc S/2004/616). Naciones Unidas (2005) Resolución 2005/81 sobre impunidad de la Comisión de Derechos Humanos de Naciones Unidas (E/CN.4/RES/2005/81). Naciones Unidas (2008) Proyecto de Observaciones Finales del Comité de Derechos Humanos. España, (UN Doc. CCPR/C/ESP/CO/5). Ortí, Alfonso (1989) Transición postfranquista a la monarquía parlamentaria y rela- ciones de clase: del desencanto programado a la socialtecnocracia transnacional, Política y Sociedad, nº 2, pp. 7-19. Paredes, José Manuel (2010) Soluciones, haberlas, haylas: acerca de garantismos falsos y desconsideraciones verdaderas hacia el derecho internacional de los Derechos http://blogs.publico.es/dominiopublico/11965/la-gran-verguenza-de-la-democracia-espanola/ http://blogs.publico.es/dominiopublico/11965/la-gran-verguenza-de-la-democracia-espanola/ Revista de Paz y Conflictos issn 1988-7221 | Vol. 9 | Nº 1 | 2016 | pp. 209-234 233 Humanos, Blog: Justicia internacional y franquismo: el caso contra Garzón. [Consulta de 4 diciembre 2015]. Paredes, José Manuel (2013) La impunidad como práctica interpretativa: sobre el desprecio de la jurisdicción penal por el Derecho internacional de los Derechos Humanos, Jueces para la Democracia, nº 76, pp. 32-40. Pérez Álvarez, Pablo (2015) La Ley de Memoria Histórica es papel mojado, CTXT – Contexto y Acción, núm. 13. En: [Consultado el 8 diciembre 2015]. Pisarello, Gerardo (2011) Un largo Termidor. La ofensiva del constitucionalismo antide- mocrático, Madrid, Trotta. Queralt, Joan (2007) Desmemoria histórica, El País, 5 enero. En: [Consultado el 4 diciem1- bre 2015]. Queralt, Joan (2011) Imposibilidades de la Ley de memoria histórica: el caso Com- panys, en Núñez Paz, Miguel Ángel (ed.) Un derecho penal comprometido. Libro ho- menaje al Prof. Dr. Gerardo Landrove Díaz, Valencia, Tirant lo Blanch, pp. 929-945. Requejo Pagés, Juan Luis (1992) Consideraciones en torno a la posición de las normas internacionales en el ordenamiento español, Revista Española de Derecho Constitu- cional, nº 34, pp. 41-66. Sáez, Ramón (2009) Justicia transicional y España. ¿Se puede juzgar la historia? en VV.AA. Memoria histórica: ¿se puede juzgar la historia?, Madrid, Fundación Antonio Carretero, pp. 85-112. Sáez, Ramón (2010) Los jueces y el aprendizaje de la impunidad, a propósito de los crímenes del franquismo, Mientras tanto, núm. 114, pp. 41-72. Sáez, Ramón (2014) Justicia universal en España: el olvido del crimen de Estado, Jueces para la Democracia, nº 80, pp. 5-11. Sánchez Cuenca, Ignacio (2007) La violencia terrorista en la transición española a la democracia, Historia del presente, nº 14, pp. 9-24. Sánchez Soler, Mariano (2010) La transición sangrienta. Una historia violenta del pro- ceso democrático en España (1975-1983), Barcelona, Península. Sauca, José María (2008) El derecho ciudadano a la memoria histórica: concepto y contenido, en Martín Pallín, José Antonio y Escudero, Rafael (eds.) Derecho y me- moria histórica, Madrid, Trotta, pp. 73-104. Share, Donald y Mainwaring, Scott (1986) Transiciones vía transacción: la democra- tización en Brasil y en España, Revista de Estudios Políticos, nº 49, pp. 87-135. Sole Tura, Jordi (1985) Nacionalidades y nacionalismos en España. Autonomías, federa- lismo y autodeterminación, Madrid, Alianza Editorial. http://casogarzon.blogspot.co.uk/2010/05/colaboraciones-jose-manuel-paredes.html http://casogarzon.blogspot.co.uk/2010/05/colaboraciones-jose-manuel-paredes.html http://ctxt.es/es/20150416/politica/806/memoria-memoria-hist%C3%B3rica-fosas-comunes-exhumaciones-ayudas-PP-Partido-Popular-recortes-Espa%C3%B1a-Desmontando-el-bienestar.htm http://ctxt.es/es/20150416/politica/806/memoria-memoria-hist%C3%B3rica-fosas-comunes-exhumaciones-ayudas-PP-Partido-Popular-recortes-Espa%C3%B1a-Desmontando-el-bienestar.htm http://ctxt.es/es/20150416/politica/806/memoria-memoria-hist%C3%B3rica-fosas-comunes-exhumaciones-ayudas-PP-Partido-Popular-recortes-Espa%C3%B1a-Desmontando-el-bienestar.htm http://elpais.com/diario/2007/01/05/espana/1167951617_850215.html http://elpais.com/diario/2007/01/05/espana/1167951617_850215.html artículos originales Payero López, Lucia. Justicia de transición en España: claves para aprobar una asignatura pendiente234 Tamarit, Josep (2009) Justicia transicional y Derecho penal en España, en VV.AA. Memoria histórica: ¿se puede juzgar la historia?, Madrid, Fundación Antonio Carre- tero, pp. 129-141. Tamarit, Josep (2010) Justicia penal, justicia reparadora y comisiones de la verdad, en Tamarit, Joset (coord.) Justicia de transición, justicia penal internacional y justicia universal, Barcelona, Atelier, pp. 45-72. Valencia, Hernando (2012) La ley española de amnistía de 1977 en una perspectiva de justicia transicional, en Ripol, Santiago y Villán, Carlos (dirs.) Justicia de transición: el caso de España, Barcelona, Institut Català Internacional per la Pau, pp. 185-198. Vicente, Lydia (2009) La obligación de investigar los crímenes del pasado y garantizar los derechos de las víctimas de desaparición forzada durante la Guerra Civil y el franquismo, en VV.AA. Memoria histórica: ¿se puede juzgar la historia?, Madrid, Fundación Antonio Carretero, pp. 143-169. Villa Gómez, Juan David (2013) Consecuencias psicosociales de la participación en escenarios de justicia transicional en un contexto de conflicto, impunidad y no- transición, Cátedra Abierta, nº 13 (2), pp. 307-338. Viver i Pi-Sunyer, Carles (1998) Veinte años de Constitución y de incipiente consti- tucionalismo, Revista de Occidente, nº 211, pp. 23-53. proceso editor i al • editor i al proccess info Recibido: 09/12/2015 Aceptado: 31/05/2016 cómo citar este artículo • how to cite this paper Payero López, Lucia (2016) Justicia de transición en España: claves para aprobar una asignatura pendiente, Revista de Paz y Conflictos, Vol. 9, nº 1, pp. 209-234. sobr e los autor es • about the authors Lucía Payero López es doctora en Derecho por la Universidad de Oviedo y colaboradora de honor del Área de Fi- losofía del Derecho de dicha Universidad. Participa como investigadora en el proyecto “Neo-federalism: Dividing Political Power among People(s)”, financiado por el Consejo de Investigación Europeo (ERC) y desarrollado en Durham Law School (UK). work_3lojazwgvjbc3e6k55gvk3z4ou ---- Book reviewvs 117 Clinical Ethics ARJonsen,M SieglerandWJ Winslade West Drayton, Collier Macmillan, 1982, £14. The subtitle of this book, which was first published in the United States, is 'A Practical Approach to Ethical Deci- sions in Clinical Medicine' and the authors are a philosopher, a clinician and a lawyer. The reader is given the benefit of a consensus, as it were, after the authors have discussed each problem amongst themselves. The book is crisp and short but there is an excellent bibliography and as well as a table of contents there is a 'locator' which is very helpful and there is good cross-referencing. These aids are important because instead of the more conventional arrangement of chapters by subject there are only four chapters: Indications for medical intervention; Patient preferences; Quality of life, and External factors. As the authors indi- cate in the introduction these titles are taken from philosophical literature and based on the 'Principle of beneficence behind indications for medical inter- vention, the principle of autonomy behind patient preferences and some form of Utilitarianism behind quality of life and external factors'. This grouping may seem awkward to the clinician but all the practical problems of day-to-day decisions are readily found and helpfully discussed. By 'clinical ethics' the authors mean 'the identification, analysis and resolution of moral problems that arise in the care of a particular patient'. The book, which fits readily into the pocket of a white coat, is intended primnarily for doctors, but it will also be helpful to medical students and to nurses. Although written for a readership in the United States, it is entirely relevant to the scene in other countries and the bibliography is international. The case histories are numerous, varied and succinct. The comments provoke thought and do not attempt to lay down dogmatically the appropriate course of action. The authors stress the very close links which should exist between the ethics component and the clinical care component for each patient. One ofthe authors, Siegler, has described elsewhere (Medical Ethics and Medical Education. Geneva; Council for International Organisation of Medical Sciences, CIOMS: 1981: 196-206) a model for the practice and teaching of clinical ethics. He emphasises that it is the clinician who can best understand the medical moral issues as problems within the context of the clinical situation. He goes on to describe his programme in clinical ethics which runs concurrently with a one-month attachment to the acute general medical unit. During the month the group often students meets three times a week for clinical ethics. The meetings are held in a conference room within the medical unit. They are inter-disciplinary and are led by a senior member of staff of the medical unit. A student presents the ethical aspects of a case currently in the unit and discussion follows. This arrangement emphasises the integration of ethics into clinical care. This is the approach which pervades Clinical Ethics and the reader feels he is taking part in such an interdisciplinary discussion on a great variety of day-to- day problems. A S DUNCAN Emeritus Professor ofMedical Education Uniersity ofEdinburgh A Christian Framework for Medical Ethics C Gordon Scorer London, Christian Medical Fellowship Publications, 1980, 50p. This is indeed a quart into a pint pot. In the course of a mere 14 pages Scorer mentions various themes. He discusses the power and responsibility of the doctor, which entails that medical ethics is vital, going far beyond medical etiquette. Another of his themes is the challenge to traditional ethics (which, one infers from what he writes, has been ofan individualist kind, focusing on the one-to-one doctor-patient relationship) by team work; by increasingly well informed patients who may well demand their rights; by new, profound, and sometimes insoluble ethical problems arising from new medical technologies and their cost, and by the increasing control over the doctor not only by his professional organisations but by the State. He argues that an ethical system is required which is consistent and comprehensive, but not legalistic. That is to be found in the Ten Commandments and Christ's expansion of them. A series of particular ethical problems are also mentioned - truth, confidentiality, consent, euthanasia, abortion, Artificial Insemination by a Donor (AID), and contraceptives for immature teenagers. The contribution of Christians to the medical profession is to stand for sound learning and to warn against covetousness. Love is their mainspring; and this may mean choosing between two evils. It certainly means avoiding sentimentality or moralism. Scorer was joint editor of a book in 1979 on moral-decision making in medicine, and there is clearly much ex- perience behind what he writes. Here he has attempted the impossible. If it is intended as a general survey to whet the appetite he should have indicated its limitations. For instance there is no hint of the problems which inevitably arise in the intermediate steps needed in moving from the Bible to particular contemporary decisions in the medical or any other field; nor is there any hint of problems when he urges his readers to press for 'sound legislation which will support Christian values rather than undermine them'. Here again agree- ment on details will raise problems among Christians themselves, apart from those of living in a plural society. The tone is admirably eirenic, as one would expect from one who refers four times to the thought of William Temple. RONALD PRESTON Faculty ofTheology University ofManchester Triage and Justice Gerald R Winslow Berkeley, Los Angeles & London, University of California Press, 1982, £15.00. Triage, the practice of screening patients in order to determine their priority for treatment, has long been a familiar aspect of military and emer- gency medicine. The word 'triage', according to the author of this valuable new book, first entered English with reference to the grading of agricul- tural products and later, during World War I, acquired its medical meaning. Put simply, the practice is based on what Winslow identifies as the principles of medical neediness and medical success: those who need treatment in order to survive are given priority over those who will recover without treatment and those who, even with treatment, will probably die. Triage has also been governed by what Winslow terms the principles of conservation and of immediate usefulness: lower priority, that is, may be given to patients whose survival requires resources, including time, sufficiently great to keep alive at least o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://jm e .b m j.co m / J M e d E th ics: first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /jm e .9 .2 .1 1 7 -b o n 1 Ju n e 1 9 8 3 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://jme.bmj.com/ 118 Book reviews two other candidates; while higher priority may be given to those, for ex- ample, doctors or nurses, whose treat- ment for less severe injuries will return them rapidly to usefulness. To those given low priority, and to those who care for them, the workings of triage may feel unfair, and the relevant decisions are often not taken without regret: but at this sharpest end ofmedi- cine, any lingering over the injustice of triage is a luxury. But what in one context is a luxury, in another may be a necessity. Triage and Justice has been written in the aware- ness that the principles of triage may be extended to other areas of medicine, particularly but not only during the development of expensive new tech- nologies. In an historically interesting introductory chapter, Winslow traces the development of triage in military medicine from the practice of Baron Larrey, Napoleon's chief medical officer (who insisted that casualties be tended 'entirely without regard to rank or distinction'), through the American Civil War and the two World Wars, to the more explicit categories of modern medico-military textbooks. By World War II triage principles had begun to be employed for large-scale allocation deci- sions (macroallocation) as well as in their original microallocation battlefield context: it was decided, for example, that soldiers and airmen suffering from gonorrhoea rather than battle casualties should be treated with the scarce re- source of penicillin, the justification being that of immediate usefulness to the war effort. In the post-war period, with the advent ofnew forms ofmedical technology and therapy, justification of macroallocation choices and their microallocation counterparts became more problematic: in the USA during the 1960s, for example, there was con- siderable public debate about the attempt, at the Seattle Artificial Kidney Centre, to formulate non-medical cri- teria for the selection of patients for the scarce resource of renal dialysis. In this debate, since the employment of such traditional triage principles as medical neediness, medical success and con- servation was unlikely to narrow the field sufficiently, other utilitarian principles such as those of parental role and value to society were suggested as ways of determining priorities; the principle of immediate usefulness moreover was adapted by some to justify giving priority to patients who could pay enough for it to meet the cost of others' treatment. But against these, other principles - of medical and general neediness, of queuing, of random selection, even ofsaving no one when all cannot be saved - were and have subsequently been advanced as criteria for these new triage choices. The introduction ofthese latter kinds of principle, which Winslow categorises as egalitarian, indicated that the utilitarian approach of military and emergency medicine was much less publicly accep- table in the civilian context. Away from the scene ofbattle or ofdisaster, in other words, the claims of justice became more pressing and demanded further discussion. Winslow's book is a useful contri- bution to this discussion. It identifies five utilitarian principles (medical suc- cess, immediate usefulness, conserva- tion, parental role and general social value) and five egalitarian (saving no one, medical neediness, general needi- ness, queuing and random selection) which have been argued for as criteria in triage, and considers each in relation to two hypothetical 'prismatic cases' (a future San Francisco earthquake and the development of an artificial heart) which illustrate different ways in which triage might be called for. Considera- tion of these principles is prefaced by a chapter in which Winslow argues per- suasively against the view that 'dire scarcity' ('the lack of a life-sustaining resource that cannot be further divided and remain effective') necessarily renders all forms of triage equally 'non- just': it would be unjust, for example, not to conduct triage impartially and also unjust not to use the scarce resource at all. On this latter basis, Winslow re- jects the egalitarian principle of saving no one, while acknowledging the moral weight of revulsion against having to make such choices at all. Addressing the question ofwhether the other principles can be ranked in some order of priority, Winslow makes use of John Rawls's much-discussed 'Theory of Justice' and in particular the ranking which might be adopted by Rawls's rational but self- interested social-contract makers behind their 'veil of ignorance' about their own individual life-chances. The result gives priority to the egalitarian criteria of medical neediness and queuing (in disasters such as the earth- quake) or random selection (for such benefits of medical advance as the arti- ficial heart). The priority offair equality of access to scarce life-saving resources, however, has to be limited by appli- cation of the utilitarian principles of medical success and conservation and (in disasters) by that of immediate use- fulness. The usefulness of giving priority in medical advance to wealthy candidates who can pay for others' treatment is admitted to be rational in microallocation, but its moral offen- siveness questions the whole market approach to health care. Rawls's con- tractors would seem unlikely to choose the US system, and in Winslow's view they would also reject both the utili- tarian criteria of parental role and general social value and, even if it could be applied, the egalitarian principle of general neediness. In reaching these conclusions, Winslow has some difficulty with Rawls's theory: as he admits, it is con- ceived for conditions ofmoderate rather than dire scarcity and for something closer to macroallocation than micro- allocation, in which Winslow is primarily interested; moreover it says too little about health and health care and too much about the contractors' parental role for Winslow's immediate purpose. The book might have been better had the author been less respect- ful towards the philosophical master and instead addressed his case more plainly in his own words to a more medical and general readership. But against this it must be admitted that leaving the security of Rawls's philo- sophical buttressing is a daunting prospect for the critic ofprevailing utili- tarianism, perhaps especially in a medical context; and Winslow's achievement in bringing the Theory of Justice this much nearer practical pro- blems is no mean one. Triage andJustice is to be recommended as an economical but comprehensive book which brings considerable clarity to many important aspects of the ethics of resource allo- cation in health care. KENNETH M BOYD Scottish Director Societyfor the Study ofMedical Ethics o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://jm e .b m j.co m / J M e d E th ics: first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /jm e .9 .2 .1 1 7 -b o n 1 Ju n e 1 9 8 3 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://jme.bmj.com/ work_3ltprtf4anck5lqvkmlfatfjza ---- Justice, Deviance, and the Dark Ghetto Justice, Deviance, and the Dark Ghetto TOMMIE SHELBY The truth of the dark ghetto is not merely a truth about Negroes; it reflects the deeper torment and anguish of the total human predicament. Kenneth B. Clark, Dark Ghetto Unjust social arrangements are themselves a kind of extortion, even violence, and consent to them does not bind. John Rawls, A Theory of Justice In the United States, some citizens sharply criticize poor people who live in ghettos. These critics demand that the urban poor take greater “per- sonal responsibility” for their choices and stop blaming the government or racism for hardships that they have imposed on themselves through self-defeating attitudes and bad conduct. The problems of the ghetto, on this view, are primarily the result of a crisis of values, best remedied by reaffirming a collective commitment to living morally upright lives. On the other side are those who criticize the government for its failure to ameliorate the social conditions of the ghetto poor. They believe the government and affluent citizens have an obligation to improve the impoverished lives of the ghetto poor and should stop “blaming the victim,” that is, should stop criticizing the poor for a situation brought about by the failure of the society to live up to its professed ideals. Rather than demand that the ghetto poor change, they argue that the social system should be made more equitable. This debate raises highly contentious and urgent practical issues. It also raises difficult philosophical questions. I am not thinking primarily about traditional problems of free will and moral responsibility. The problems I will focus on lie in the domain of the theory of justice. Spe- cifically, my concern is to determine what kinds of criticisms of the ghetto poor’s behavior and attitudes are or are not appropriate given that © 2007 by Blackwell Publishing, Inc. Philosophy & Public Affairs 35, no. 2 the social circumstances under which they make their life choices are, at least in part, the result of injustice. If the overall social arrangement in which the ghetto poor live is unjust, this requires that we think about what their obligations are quite differently than we should if the society were judged to be just.1 In particular, I will argue that it is necessary to distinguish the civic obligations citizens have to each other from the natural duties all persons have as moral agents, both of which are affected, though in different ways, by the justness of social arrange- ments. In addition, among the natural duties all persons possess is the duty to uphold, and to assist in bringing about, just institutions, a politi- cal duty that has important, though generally overlooked, consequences for the debate about ghetto poverty. Throughout I will stress the importance of assessing the moral status of the ghetto poor’s conduct within nonideal political theory, that under- developed part of the theory of justice that specifies how we should respond to or rectify injustice. This is not, of course, the only relevant evaluative point of view. It is, however, a crucial and frequently neglected one, at least when it comes to thinking about the conduct of poor urban blacks. In addition, viewing these problems from the stand- point of justice—rather than, say, that of traditional American values or I have benefited greatly from discussions of drafts of this article with seminar partici- pants and audiences at UC Berkeley, Princeton University, Columbia University, the Society for the Study of Africana Philosophy, Harvard University, University of Toronto, and a moral philosophy conference in Dubrovnik, Croatia, sponsored by Ohio State Uni- versity, University of Maribor, and University of Rijeka. For comments and discussion, I’m grateful to Anthony Appiah, Nir Eyal, Samuel Freeman, Niko Kolodny, Angelika Krebs, Ron Mallon, John Pittman, Amélie Rorty, Jessie Scanlon, Tim Scanlon, Samuel Scheffler, Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, Melissa Williams, William Julius Wilson, and the Editors of Philosophy & Public Affairs. Research for this article was generously supported by the Center for Human Values at Princeton University. 1. Norman Daniels makes this important point when discussing how the “context of compliance” (i.e., the extent to which social institutions satisfy appropriate principles of justice) affects how we should assess the relative priority of (i) providing adequate welfare benefits to the poor, (ii) avoiding the creation of work disincentives, and (iii) maintaining equity between low-income earners. Most relevant to my concerns is Daniels’s claim, which I believe is correct, that the extent to which background conditions are unjust will have implications for determining who among the jobless poor are blameworthy for failing or refusing to work. (See his “Conflicting Objectives and the Priorities Problem,” in Income Support: Conceptual and Policy Issues, ed. Peter G. Brown, Conrad Johnson, and Paul Vernier [Totowa, N.J.: Rowman and Littlefield, 1981], pp. 147–64.) I develop and draw out the consequences of this insight for the debate over the obligations of the ghetto poor. 127 Justice, Deviance, and the Dark Ghetto technocratic social engineering—would, I believe, help to move us beyond the behavior-versus-structure impasse that afflicts current public discussions of race and urban poverty.2 To avoid misunderstanding, a few further introductory remarks are in order. I use the word ‘deviant’ throughout in its literal sense: sharply divergent from widely accepted norms. In using this term, which I concede is not wholly satisfactory, I am not endorsing its negative con- notations or expressing disapproval.3 Moreover, there are many different attitudes and behavior associated with the ghetto that some regard, whether rightly or wrongly, as deviant or even pathological. Not all of these are relevant to my argument. The principal forms of deviance I will discuss are crime, refusing to work in legitimate jobs, and having con- tempt for authority. i. justice and the basic structure To define the problem I will rely on some familiar notions from John Rawls’s theoretical framework: justice as fairness. Some hold that Rawls’s theory of domestic justice is too austere and utopian. So to address those less sympathetic to his account and to show that my conclusions rest on relatively weak normative principles, I will make my argument in a way that does not depend on the soundness of the overall Rawlsian apparatus or on its most demanding egalitarian claims. Instead, I will limit myself to a few core yet moderate ideas from this 2. Recent work in sociology has attempted to transcend the behavior-versus-structure debate by carefully demonstrating the subtle interaction between structural and cultural factors in the explanation of ghetto conditions. See, for example, Douglas S. Massey and Nancy A. Denton, American Apartheid: Segregation and the Making of the Underclass (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1993); William Julius Wilson, When Work Disappears: The World of the New Urban Poor (New York: Knopf, 1999); and Elijah Ander- son, Code of the Street: Decency, Violence, and the Moral Life of the Inner City (New York: Norton, 1999). Unfortunately, journalistic writing, public debate, and elite political dis- course do not generally reflect this more nuanced view of urban poverty. 3. For helpful discussions of how the public discourse surrounding urban poverty, including social scientific discourse, is often stigmatizing and even racist, see Michael B. Katz, The Undeserving Poor: From the War on Poverty to the War on Welfare (New York: Pantheon, 1990); Herbert J. Gans, The War Against the Poor: The Underclass and Antipoverty Policy (New York: Basic, 1995); Martin Gilens, Why Americans Hate Welfare: Race, Media, and the Politics of Antipoverty Policy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1999); and Ange-Marie Hancock, The Politics of Disgust: The Public Identity of the Welfare Queen (New York: NYU Press, 2004). 128 Philosophy & Public Affairs well-known theory, ideas that have an intuitive appeal because they are available in our public political culture.4 Rawls suggests that if we were to conceive of society as a system of social cooperation over time and take an impartial view of what the distribution of benefits and burdens of participating in this scheme ought to be, we could arrive at objective conclusions about what social justice requires. This is not a sociological claim. Thinking of society as a fair system of cooperation is a moral idea. Social justice is defined by the set of legiti- mate claims and obligations individuals have within a fair overall social arrangement. Thought about this way, justice is, at least in part, a matter of reciprocity between persons who regard each other as equals.5 Taking this approach to questions of social justice is particularly helpful when considering criticisms often made against the ghetto poor. It provides a framework for asking when the urban poor are doing their fair share in upholding the scheme of cooperation and when they are receiving the fair share due them as equal participants in this scheme. Rawls also emphasizes the paramount significance of the basic struc- ture for social justice. The basic structure is constituted by the way the major social, political, and economic institutions of society apportion the benefits and burdens of social cooperation. A well-organized and impartially administered basic structure may not be all we need to achieve or maintain social justice. Yet it should be clear why Rawls chooses to focus on it: the effects of the basic structure on an individu- al’s life prospects are immense and wide-ranging, and these effects have an impact on the quality of individuals’ lives from the cradle to the grave.6 Given that each of us must make a life for ourselves under the dominion of such institutions, we each have a legitimate claim that these institutions treat us fairly. The institutions of the basic structure fix a person’s initial position within society, and some individuals will be more, and some less, favored in the distribution of benefits 4. An additional advantage of drawing on Rawls’s theory is that it allows me to rebut the charge, frequently made by Critical Race Theorists and others on the Left, that this brand of liberalism, like its classical ancestor, has little insightful to say about issues of race and class. 5. John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996), pp. 15–18. 6. John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, rev. ed. (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1999), p. 82; and Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, ed. Erin Kelly (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2001), p. 55. 129 Justice, Deviance, and the Dark Ghetto and burdens—of liberties, duties, opportunities, and material advan- tages—of this association over the course of their lives depending on their starting places within the social arrangement. This does not mean that a person’s life prospects are completely determined by the particular social circumstances he or she is born into, since a person’s own choices, the good or bad will of other individuals, and brute luck will have a significant impact as well; and of course in a liberal democratic regime, where individual autonomy is (or at least ought to be) respected, each person should take primary responsibility for how his or her life goes. But each individual’s life prospects are obvi- ously deeply shaped by a social structure that he or she did not choose. Moreover, it is largely through institutions—governments, schools, firms, markets, and families—that social, natural, and fortuitous contin- gencies come to affect our individual life chances. Thus the social arrangement we participate in should be organized to give each of us a fair chance to flourish. And on Rawls’s theory, providing that fair chance means ensuring that no citizen’s life prospects are diminished because the social scheme disadvantages him or her in ways that cannot be jus- tified on impartial grounds. It is also important to outline how we should understand racial justice.7 It is now a widely shared moral conviction that racial discrimination is unjust.8 But there is considerable disagreement over what such discrimi- nation consists in. Some think that racial discrimination must be moti- vated by racial animus or an explicit intention to exclude on racial grounds. Others believe that racial discrimination occurs whenever race is considered in decisions about how public institutions ought to treat persons, even if the proposed race-conscious policy is designed to promote some otherwise worthy social goal, such as reducing the eco- nomic marginalization of groups who have been historically oppressed or attenuating the legacy of racial exclusion by creating integrated schools 7. The remarks in this paragraph and the next are developed in greater detail in my “Race and Social Justice: Rawlsian Considerations,” Fordham Law Review 72 (2004): 1697– 1715; and “Is Racism in the ‘Heart’?” Journal of Social Philosophy 33 (2002): 411–20. 8. For evidence of this, see Howard Schuman, Charlotte Steeh, Lawrence Bobo, and Maria Krysan, Racial Attitudes in America: Trends and Interpretations, rev. ed. (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1997). 130 Philosophy & Public Affairs and neighborhoods.9 Rejecting both views, I hold that racial discrimina- tion is operating when a so-called racial characteristic (or set of charac- teristics) possessed by or attributed to the members of a social group is wrongly treated as a source or sign of disvalue, incompetence, or inferi- ority. Thus, racial animus is not a necessary condition for racial discrimi- nation, and not every invocation of race in public life constitutes discrimination, at least not if “discrimination” suggests unfairness. When the administration of the institutions of the basic structure is distorted by racial prejudice or bias, Rawls regards this as a violation of “formal justice.”10 Building on this, we can say that institutional racism exists when the administration or enforcement of the rules and proce- dures of a major social institution—say, the labor market or the criminal justice system—is regularly distorted by the racial prejudice or bias of those who exercise authority within the institution. Institutional racism can exist even when the content of the rules and procedures of an insti- tution, when viewed in the abstract, is perfectly just, provided there is pervasive racial bias in the application of those rules and procedures. Rawls also allows that in some societies, for instance, those with a long history of racism, it may be necessary to make special constitutional provisions that explicitly prohibit racial discrimination in the institu- tions of the basic structure, and even to grant special powers to the government to ensure that all citizens, regardless of their race, receive the equal protection of the laws.11 The core moral idea behind the prin- ciples of racial justice, and an obviously attractive one, is that in a just society each has a chance to carry out his or her own plan of life without being unfairly inhibited in this pursuit by others’ racial prejudice or racial bias. Some think that equal opportunity exists if no important position or good afforded by social cooperation is unfairly denied persons on account of their race, ethnicity, gender, sexual orientation, disability, religion, creed, or national origin. On this view, equal opportunity is simply non- discrimination. However, Rawls thinks of equal opportunity as entailing 9. For forceful criticisms of this “colorblind” principle, see Bernard R. Boxill, Blacks and Social Justice, rev. ed. (Lanham, Md.: Rowman and Littlefield, 1992), chap. 1. Also see Glenn C. Loury, The Anatomy of Racial Inequality (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2002), chap. 4. 10. Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 51. 11. Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 173–74. 131 Justice, Deviance, and the Dark Ghetto much more than this. In particular, he thinks fair equality of opportunity requires equal life prospects (as measured by primary social goods) given similar natural talents and motivation. One should be able to expect similar income and wealth over a life as anyone else who has the same abilities and the same willingness to use them regardless of the social class one has been born into. There should be no class barriers to the acquisi- tion of knowledge or the development of skills, which means that the educational system must be set up and administered so that each has the same chance to cultivate his or her abilities regardless of class origins. This brief description of the moral ideal of racial equality and equal opportunity within a fair basic structure is perhaps too abstract. To make these principles more concrete, let me describe an embodied institu- tional arrangement that seems, on its face, to violate them. Suppose that the basic structure of a liberal democratic, market-based society has the following characteristics. There is uneven growth and decline across different sectors of the economy; however, the government does not ensure that workers hit hardest by economic restructuring, declining wages, or periodic recessions are able to maintain their standard of living. For example, there is little attempt to provide retraining pro- grams, jobs in the public sector, or subsidized income for laborers in declining industries. In general, the economy is not structured to sustain full employment at decent wages, so there are always a significant number of unemployed persons who find it difficult to find a good job. Social entitlements are so meager that many of the unemployed are forced to live in poverty while they look for work, and some do not qualify for public subsidies at all. Let us also suppose that in this same society, there is, and has been for some time, a vastly higher rate of social mobility for the highly educated than for the poorly educated. However, the quality of kindergarten to grade 12 education varies widely from neighborhood to neighborhood. In affluent, middle-class, and mixed-income suburban neighborhoods, the public schools are generally good; in urban working-class and poor neighborhoods, the education offered is often significantly inferior and substandard. Yet despite these manifest and widely known inequities between suburban and urban schools, the government does not distrib- ute resources in a way to create equal educational opportunity across different neighborhoods, and most citizens in suburban communities do not push for a more equitable allotment of educational resources. 132 Philosophy & Public Affairs Finally, let us assume that this society is a multiracial one, with a white majority and several smaller nonwhite racial groups. The society has a long and brutal history of racial domination, exploitation, and exclusion. Indeed, it was once based on explicit white supremacist principles; and it practiced race-based slavery and de jure racial segregation enforced through terror. These practices have now been abolished, and constitu- tional and legislative provisions have been enacted to give racial minori- ties equal civil rights. Explicit expressions of racist attitudes have declined sharply. Nevertheless, covert forms of racial prejudice still exist and attenuate the impartial administration of the major institutions of the society. Antidiscrimination law is not effectively enforced, and too often, one must hire a private attorney to make sure one’s formal rights are adequately protected. Ongoing racial discrimination in employment and housing is a particularly acute problem and has a disproportionate negative impact on the poorer members of racial minority groups, as the education, financial resources, and social capital of more advantaged members allow them greater social mobility despite continuing racism. If under this institutional arrangement the tax scheme allows enor- mous intergenerational wealth transfers within families, some families will maintain considerable socioeconomic advantages over others, which allows them to provide better educations and better environ- ments (both residential and familial) for their children, and their chil- dren’s children. Moreover, the wealthy and well educated will be greatly advantaged in the competition for positions of political authority, so that their superior material assets and educational opportunities will often be tickets to political power, augmenting their already disproportionate influence on government policy via campaign contributions and sup- port for various lobbying efforts. Even in a constitutional democracy in which each citizen has a publicly recognized claim to all the basic politi- cal and civil liberties, these socioeconomic inequalities would create an informal social hierarchy by birth: some would be born into great wealth and other social and political advantages while others would be born into poverty and its associated disadvantages. Rawls thinks that such inequities are manifestly incompatible with basic fairness, for he believes that each citizen should have roughly equal life chances and equal prospects for influencing public policy. There are of course many who think that the fair equality of opportu- nity principle is too strong, demanding too much equality. And there are 133 Justice, Deviance, and the Dark Ghetto those who reject all egalitarian interpretations of the equal opportunity principle. Still, if, because a social scheme had the characteristics described above, the life prospects of some children were vastly inferior to those of others, it would be reasonable to regard these disadvantaged children as members of the lowest stratum in a descent-based social hierarchy. When such a hierarchy is, and has long been, marked by racial distinctions, equal citizenship, in any meaningful sense, does not obtain.12 In a society with an established democratic tradition, such a quasi-feudal order does not warrant the allegiance of its most disadvan- taged members, especially when these persons are racially stigmatized. Indeed, the existence of such an order creates the suspicion that, despite the society’s ostensible commitment to equal civil rights, white supremacy has simply taken a new form. ii. deviance as a response to the ghetto plight Ghettos are defined by three core characteristics: race, urban location, and poverty. In the United States, ghettos are generally understood to be (1) predominantly black, (2) urban neighborhoods, (3) with high concen- trations of poverty.13 Although ghettos exist in other advanced capitalist societies and my analysis is relevant to them as well, the issues of justice that U.S. ghettos raise are especially acute and in some ways unique.14 Of course, there are poor neighborhoods in the United States that are not predominantly black, and much of what I will go on to say about black ghettos (or analogous things) could be said about white slums, Latino 12. For a classic discussion of the relationship between being respected as an equal and the principle of equal opportunity, see Bernard Williams, “The Idea of Equality,” in his In the Beginning Was the Deed: Realism and Moralism in Political Argument, ed. Geoffrey Hawthorn (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2005), pp. 97–114. 13. See Paul A. Jargowsky, Poverty and Place: Ghettos, Barrios, and the American City (New York: Russell Sage Foundation, 1997), pp. 12–17. 14. For comparative accounts of U.S. ghettos with similar urban communities in Western European societies, see Barbara Schmitter Heisler, “A Comparative Perspective on the Underclass: Questions of Urban Poverty, Race, and Citizenship,” Theory and Society 20 (1991): 455–483; Loïc J. D. Wacquant, “The Rise of Advanced Marginality: Notes on Its Nature and Implications,” Acta Sociologica 39 (1996): 121–39; and Roger Lawson and William Julius Wilson, “Poverty, Social Rights, and the Quality of Citizenship,” in Poverty, Inequality, and the Future of Social Policy: Western States in the New World Order, ed. Katherine McFate, Roger Lawson, and William Julius Wilson (New York: Russell Sage Foundation, 1995), pp. 693–714. 134 Philosophy & Public Affairs barrios, some Indian reservations, and some Asian communities.15 I focus on black ghettos because they figure most prominently in the public imagination as enclaves of the pathological “underclass” and they are an especially salient example of the problems of racial and economic justice I am concerned with. I focus on high-poverty urban neighbor- hoods rather than on poor people wherever they happen to live because the high concentration of poverty in inner-city neighborhoods is associ- ated with behavior and attitudes that are not only deviant (i.e., in sharp conflict with commonly accepted norms) but are also widely perceived as a threat to the freedom, property, and safety of others and that there- fore lead some to regard many in such neighborhoods as not deserving of further government attempts to improve their lot. I should emphasize that many who live under ghetto conditions respect the law, accept conventional morality, and make an effort to conform to “mainstream” standards of public and private conduct. Some accept dead-end, menial, and low-wage jobs as they struggle to maintain a decent life for themselves and their families.16 Most value work and desire to be economically self-sufficient.17 Some graduate from high school or pass the GED; some of these get post-secondary educa- tion or job training; and a few even go on to graduate from college. In 15. These other ethnoracial minority communities present complications for questions of justice that black ghettos generally do not. For instance, many Asian enclaves and Latino barrios contain large numbers of first-generation immigrants. Fair equality of opportunity is not an appropriate standard for judging whether immigrants are treated fairly by the social system. Their place in the system did not begin at birth, and their life prospects will obviously depend, not only on whether they receive fair treatment in the United States, but also on the social advantages or disadvantages (e.g., in education and wealth) they had in their country of origin prior to immigration. Many from poor countries can substantially improve their material condition by immigrating to the United States, and so some do not resent the existing opportunity structure but are often grateful for the chance to enhance their lives, even if that chance is not equal to that of native-born citizens. Moreover, unlike native-born black Americans, immigrants generally have the option to return to their country of origin. Indians who live on reservations, on the other hand, are nations or quasi-nations unto themselves, with some rights of group self-determination. The recog- nized group rights and treaties between indigenous peoples and the United States com- plicate questions of social justice for Native Americans. African Americans, while a protected group under antidiscrimination law, do not enjoy such group-based rights, although I do not mean to imply that they should. 16. Katherine S. Newman, No Shame in My Game: The Working Poor in the Inner City (New York: Vintage and Russell Sage, 1999). 17. Wilson, When Work Disappears, pp. 67–70. 135 Justice, Deviance, and the Dark Ghetto short, a substantial segment of the ghetto poor are not alienated from the wider society, its major institutions, or its basic social norms.18 However, many are alienated, some deeply so. High-poverty neighborhoods with few good employment options and poor schools lead some residents, especially those unemployed for long periods, to consider securing income through illegitimate means.19 Ghetto poverty creates desperation and feelings of shame, and some, seeking to escape the weight of their social conditions, or at least to make it more bearable, resort to crime. Of course, crime does not just occur in the ghetto. People from all races, classes, and types of neighborhood engage in criminal activity for money, status, power, or amusement. When persons from the ghetto choose crime, however, they do so under conditions of material deprivation and institutional racism. Thus their criminal activity might express something more, or something other, than a character flaw or a disregard for the authority of morality. Some rely on crime to supplement legitimate income derived from work, welfare benefits, or private aid. Others, such as those who have dropped out of the legitimate labor market altogether, do not qualify for welfare benefits, or cannot rely on kin support, use crime as their primary source of income. Although the line is fine and easy to cross, some persons commit crimes without allowing “the streets” to define their social identity or corrupt their souls.20 Nevertheless, to engage profitably in street crime one must develop the appropriate skills, strat- egies, and dispositions. This repertoire is simply street capital, assets that one can use to secure income in the underground urban economy. Just as one may use financial capital without being, strictly speaking, a “capitalist,” one can draw on street capital without being a “criminal.”21 However, crime can become a vocation, and as such it has its own set 18. See Jennifer L. Hochschild, Facing Up to the American Dream: Race, Class, and the Soul of the Nation (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1995), chap. 4. 19. As with the term ‘deviant,’ by ‘illegitimate’ I do not mean ‘unjustified.’ That would beg the question. Rather, these are means, should one use them, that would violate widely recognized behavioral norms, whether legal, moral, or traditional. These norms can be “legitimate,” in the relevant sense, without being fully justified. 20. See Sudhir Alladi Venkatesh, Off the Books: The Underground Economy of the Urban Poor (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2006). 21. It is just this distinction between having committed criminal acts and being habitu- ally disposed to criminal behavior that is elided in Michael Levin, “Responses to Race Differences in Crime,” Journal of Social Philosophy 23 (1992): 5–29. 136 Philosophy & Public Affairs of disciplines or what I will call “ethics.” There are two broad criminal ethics that I want briefly to describe. Note that these descriptions are to be understood as ideal types, constructed to highlight the core features of a particular action-orientation by abstracting away from character- istics that are extraneous. Real people will rarely embody these ethics consistently or fully, although some may aspire to. “Gangsters” use violence, threats, and intimidation to forcibly extract money, goods, and services from others. They are fearless and use force or the threat of it to get what they want. They are skilled fighters and adept at the use of weapons. They can strike fear in their victims with little effort. To achieve their aims, they maim and even kill, sometimes without mercy or remorse. The criminal domain they operate in includes robbery, gam- bling rackets, loan sharking, and extortion. “Hustlers,” by contrast, use deception, manipulation, and treachery to achieve their objectives. They are skillful liars. They are cunning and proficient at subtly exploiting their victims’ personal weaknesses. As amateur psychologists, they have a gift for understanding human nature, a talent they use to garner their victims’ trust, only to betray them. Their domain includes theft, fraud, prostitu- tion, and swindling. Both gangsters and hustlers flout the law and have little if any respect for the authority of mainstream institutions. These attitudes are appropriate to their trade; it is rational to cultivate them once one has chosen street crime as a way of life.22 It should go without saying that these two ethics are not mutually exclusive; one need only consider the modus operandi of many pimps.23 Nowhere is this more obvious, however, than in the selling of illegal drugs in the ghetto. Although few accumulate significant wealth from it, the selling of illegal narcotics is a way to make money fast, as there is regular demand, especially for cocaine, heroin, and amphetamines. This feature of the trade provides a strong incentive to turn to it when in pressing finan- cial need. It is also a dangerous business, however, and in an era of 22. The “gangster” and the “hustler” are familiar social identities in poor urban com- munities, and these terms are generally associated with male personas and activities. In adopting these urban vernacular expressions, I do not mean to imply that only men and boys perform these roles or accept their associated ethics. Moreover, both men and women, boys and girls, use street capital and deploy the tactics and strategies of gangsters and hustlers, though obviously not always in the same ways or with the same frequency. 23. See my “Parasites, Pimps, and Capitalists: A Naturalistic Conception of Exploita- tion,” Social Theory and Practice 28 (2002): 381–418. 137 Justice, Deviance, and the Dark Ghetto law-and-order politics—with its accelerated growth in the penal system, widespread punitive attitudes, aggressive policing, limitations on judi- cial discretion in sentencing, and increased prosecutorial authority—it can lead to long prison terms.24 Those who practice the trade successfully and are willing to accept these risks and costs sometimes come to whole- heartedly identify with the gangster-hustler ethic. Gang members often embrace this ethic and develop forms of group solidarity in order to defend their financial interests against rival gangs. Those who join these gangs are generally expected and encouraged to show loyalty to other members but not to outsiders.25 Many who engage in street crime are eventually caught and spend time in federal penitentiaries, state prisons, county jails, or juvenile detention centers. Under state confinement, the street repertoire is aug- mented, the gangster-hustler ethics are reinforced, and hostility toward the institutions and officials of the criminal justice system hardens.26 Once released, the incentive to return to crime often increases, as the ex-convict’s job prospects and earning potential are even dimmer with a criminal record.27 The constant cycling of increasing numbers of people from ghetto to prison and back again spreads a criminal-minded ethos, an outlaw subculture, throughout many poor urban areas. The norms that govern the world of street crime also have an enor- mous impact on ghetto residents who want to avoid criminal deviance.28 For example, the widespread use of guns among drug dealers and muggers creates a demand for these weapons in ghetto neighborhoods. Because they believe the police cannot be relied upon to provide adequate security, many residents, including children, arm themselves 24. See Bruce Western, Punishment and Inequality in America (New York: Russell Sage Foundation, 2006), chap. 3; Lawrence D. Bobo and Devon Johnson, “A Taste for Punishment: Black and White Americans’ Views on the Death Penalty and the War on Drugs,” Du Bois Review 1 (2004): 151–80; and Randall Kennedy, Race, Crime, and the Law (New York: Vintage Books, 1997), chap. 10. 25. Sudhir Alladi Venkatesh and Steven D. Levitt, “ ‘Are We a Family or a Business?’ History and Disjuncture in the Urban American Street Gang,” Theory and Society 29 (2000): 427–62. 26. Loïc Wacquant, “Deadly Symbiosis: When Ghetto and Prison Meet and Mesh,” Punishment and Society 3 (2001): 95–133. 27. Western, Punishment and Inequality, chap. 5. 28. Venkatesh, Off the Books; Wilson, When Work Disappears, pp. 59–72; and Anderson, Code of the Street, chap. 3. 138 Philosophy & Public Affairs for protection.29 A looming sense of danger and a high propensity for violent interpersonal conflict sow seeds of distrust in ghetto neighbor- hoods, making it difficult for a broad sense of community to form or be maintained. Residents are always on guard and view strangers with sus- picion, for one can never be sure that others are not looking to take advantage of you. In adapting to these conditions, many residents not directly involved in crime develop survival strategies that are similar to or mimic the strategies of gangsters and hustlers. To avoid being victim- ized one must appear shrewd and capable of defending oneself, with deadly violence if necessary. Here the familiar male adolescent desire to appear “tough” can take on lethal dimensions, with frightening conse- quences for those who live in urban communities; and many adolescent girls, though under somewhat less pressure to display a readiness to resort to violence, are also drawn into some of these antisocial roles. Under these conditions a ghetto subculture emerges, where the traits of the gangster and hustler, usually condemned in mainstream society, are sometimes viewed as virtues. So far I have not mentioned the racial significance of deviance in ghetto communities. Yet this dimension is crucial to understanding the choices many poor urban blacks make. Notwithstanding the widespread belief that racism is a thing of the past and the growing demand for color-blind public policy, racial prejudice continues to have a negative impact on the life chances of racial minorities in the United States, especially black citizens.30 The impact of institutional racism is deepest in dark ghettos, because here racism and extreme poverty combine to create a uniquely stigmatized subgroup of the black population. The peculiar conse- quences of this dynamic, especially when joined with the ghetto subcul- ture just described, play themselves out in many arenas, but here 29. Jeffrey Fagan and Deanna L. Wilkinson, “Guns, Youth Violence, and Social Identity in Inner Cities,” in Crime and Justice, Vol. 24, ed. Michael Tonry and Mark H. Moore (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998), pp. 104–88. 30. See, for example, Lawrence Bobo, James R. Klugel, and Ryan A. Smith, “Laissez- Faire Racism: The Crystallization of a Kinder, Gentler, Antiblack Ideology,” in Racial Atti- tudes in the 1990s, ed. Steven A. Tuch and Jack K. Martin (Westport, Conn.: Praeger, 1997), pp. 15–41; Thomas C. Holt, The Problem of Race in the Twenty-First Century (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2000); Tali Mendelberg, The Race Card: Campaign Strat- egy, Implicit Messages, and the Norm of Equality (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2001); and Michael K. Brown, Martin Carnoy, Elliot Currie, Troy Duster, David B. Oppenheimer, Marjorie M. Shultz, and David Wellman, Whitewashing Race: The Myth of a Color-Blind Society (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2003). 139 Justice, Deviance, and the Dark Ghetto I focus on just three: employment, housing, and the criminal justice system. Many working-age ghetto residents have little education, are low skilled, and have gone long periods without legitimate jobs. In the urban labor market there are often many more applicants for low-skilled jobs than there are jobs available, so employers can afford to be selective, engaging in so-called statistical discrimination. These employers are aware that a criminal subculture affects social life in the ghetto, that there are high drop-out rates among urban blacks, and that many poor people do not work regularly. This leads some employers to expect blacks from the ghetto to be generally violent, dishonest, unreliable, and ignorant.31 Because of longstanding racial stereotypes, the high fre- quency of these traits among the ghetto poor may seem to lend credence to racist beliefs. For example, the joblessness of some ghetto residents will appear to many employers as laziness and this is of course a stereo- type that blacks strongly resent.32 One consequence of all this is that many employers avoid hiring blacks from the ghetto when they can find nonblack or suburban workers, and given the surplus of low-skilled workers in the labor pool this is easily accomplished. The racialized stigma attached to the ghetto affects the job prospects of all its black residents, even those who reject the outlaw ethic and seek to conform to mainstream norms. The frustration of dealing with racial discrimination by employers leads more blacks into the criminal subculture than would otherwise end up there. Many of those who want to find work probably could if they were able to move to suburban neighborhoods or integrated mixed-income urban areas. There tend to be considerably more job opportunities for 31. Joleen Kirschenmen and Kathryn M. Neckerman, “ ‘We’d Love to Hire Them, But . . .’: The Meaning of Race for Employers,” in The Urban Underclass, ed. Christopher Jencks and Paul E. Peterson (Washington, D.C.: Brookings Institution, 1991), pp. 203–32; and Wilson, When Work Disappears, chap. 5. 32. For a general account of how racist beliefs and attitudes reproduce oppressive conditions, see my “Ideology, Racism, and Critical Social Theory,” Philosophical Forum 34 (2003): 153–88. Also see Robert Miles, Racism (London: Routledge, 1989); Barbara J. Fields, “Slavery, Race and Ideology in the United States of America,” New Left Review 181 (1990): 95–118; John T. Jost and Mahzarin R. Banaji, “The Role of Stereotyping in System- Justification and the Production of False Consciousness,” British Journal of Social Psychol- ogy (1994): 1–27; Bobo, Klugel, and Smith, “Laissez-Faire Racism”; and Jim Sidanius and Felicia Pratto, Social Dominance: An Intergroup Theory of Social Hierarchy and Oppression (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), chap. 4. 140 Philosophy & Public Affairs low-skilled workers in these areas than in or near the ghetto.33 Schools are of much higher quality there too. Housing is more expensive in these other communities, however, often way out of reach for poor people.34 Most middle-class people, including many middle-class blacks, do not want to live among the ghetto poor and do not want their children to be forced to attend the same schools with them either; thus they are willing to pay a high premium to reside in better neighborhoods, driving up already high housing costs. Yet it would be a mistake to think that the black poor find it so hard to exit the ghetto solely because of the uncoordinated decisions of indi- viduals or impersonal market forces (and even if these factors were the complete explanation, it would not follow that justice permits us to tol- erate these unintended consequences). Racial discrimination in housing and practices of neighborhood organizations designed to segregate poor blacks in the inner city (including opposition to busing and advocacy of neighborhood schools) also play a large part.35 Therefore it is enor- mously difficult for the black poor to escape ghettos, since either they cannot afford to move out or residents of nonghetto areas, whether because of racial prejudice, class bias, or narrow self-interest, inhibit the ability of the urban poor to join these better communities or attend high-quality schools. Many of the black urban poor are effectively con- fined to ghetto neighborhoods, isolated from the rest of society.36 They 33. William Julius Wilson, The Truly Disadvantaged: The Inner City, the Underclass, and Public Policy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987), pp. 39–46; and John D. Kasarda, “Urban Industrial Transition and the Underclass,” in The Ghetto Underclass: Social Science Perspectives, updated edition, ed. William Julius Wilson (Newbury Park, Calif.: Sage Publi- cations, 1993), pp. 43–64. 34. Low-skilled inner-city workers could also get to jobs in the suburbs if they had cars, which most cannot afford. Public transportation systems in most metropolitan areas are woefully inefficient, creating long commuting times, and are often too expensive for the working poor to use daily. 35. Massey and Denton, American Apartheid; Mary Pattillo-McCoy, Black Picket Fences: Privilege and Peril Among the Black Middle Class (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1999); Camille Zubrinsky Charles, Won’t You Be My Neighbor? Race, Class, and Resi- dence in Los Angeles (New York: Russell Sage Foundation, 2006); and William Julius Wilson and Richard P. Taub, There Goes the Neighborhood (New York: Knopf, 2006). 36. It is worth noting that the ghetto poor do sometimes manage to exit poor neigh- borhoods but then only to return to the same or a similar neighborhood shortly thereafter. Indeed, some are able to move to nonpoor neighborhoods and then these new neighbor- hoods become poor later, as more poor people move in and the nonpoor move out. For many poor urban blacks, the problem is not so much getting out of the ghetto but staying 141 Justice, Deviance, and the Dark Ghetto must therefore confront the miserable job prospects and failing schools that exist in the inner core of U.S. metropolises. Faced with these tremendous obstacles, many choose to drop out of the legitimate labor market, turning to illegitimate means to generate income. One of the many tragic consequences of this situation is the mass incarceration of poor black people, especially young black men.37 Despite making up only 13 percent of the male population of the United States, black men constitute almost half of the male prison population, and on any given day, nearly a third of all black men in their twenties are in prison, on probation, or on parole.38 These black men are overwhelmingly from ghetto communities. The high levels of police surveillance, racial profil- ing, stiff penalties for minor parole violations, felon disenfranchisement laws, and general harassment of young urban blacks intensify their hos- tility toward the criminal justice system, and invite urban blacks to con- clude that they are living under a race-based police state whose intent is to prevent them from enjoying all the benefits of equal citizenship and to contain social unrest. Because of the extreme racial disparity in the numbers of persons under the supervision of the criminal justice system, the general stigma attached to a criminal conviction taints all blacks, especially young black men and boys from the ghetto. Moreover, black urban youth are sometimes seen as having a propensity to criminal behavior.39 These factors greatly disadvantage those from the ghetto who seek employment, decent housing, and good schools, for they are too often presumed to be (“naturally”) prone to lawlessness. To be clear, I am not denying the obvious fact that some born into ghetto poverty can, and do, manage to escape poverty and the ghetto, out. See Lincoln Quillian, “How Long Are Exposures to Poor Neighborhoods? The Long- Term Dynamics of Entry and Exit from Poor Neighborhoods,” Population Research and Policy Review 22 (2003): 221–49. 37. Becky Pettit and Bruce Western, “Mass Imprisonment and the Life Course: Race and Class Inequality in U.S. Incarceration,” American Sociological Review 69 (2004): 151–69; Loïc Wacquant, “From Slavery to Mass Incarceration: Rethinking the ‘Race Question’ in the U.S.,” New Left Review 13 (2002): 41–60; see also Wacquant, “Deadly Symbiosis.” For a concise summary of the racist causes and racial consequences of mass incarceration in the United States, see Brian Barry, Why Social Justice Matters (Cambridge: Polity, 2005), chap. 7. 38. Marc Mauer, Race to Incarcerate (New York: New Press, 1999). 39. Lincoln Quillian and Devah Pager, “Black Neighbors, Higher Crime? The Role of Racial Stereotypes in Evaluations of Neighborhood Crime,” American Journal of Sociology 107 (2001): 717–67. 142 Philosophy & Public Affairs whether through state assistance, the help of other people, sheer per- sonal determination, or good luck. Yet if an unjust basic structure is a significant causal factor in explaining the rise and persistence of ghetto conditions and such conditions diminish the life prospects of citizens who live under them, the fact that some from the ghetto are still able to improve their lot through legitimate means and ultimately to leave the ghetto does not invalidate the claim for redress of those who remain behind. After all, some enslaved blacks during the antebellum era were eventually able to buy their freedom or were voluntarily released by their owners, and some southern blacks attained middle-class economic status through hard work and perseverance despite Jim Crow segrega- tion and the terror of the Klan. Although the racial status hierarchy in the United States is itself largely impermeable, it has never been so powerful that all blacks are confined to the lowest socioeconomic strata. The obstacles that the system continues to place in the way of poor blacks, though in some ways less burdensome than in the past, are nevertheless objectionable on grounds of justice. iii. is deviance reasonable? Imprudence is rightly regarded as a vice, and some of the choices ghetto residents make are no doubt unwise, given their risks, costs, and nega- tive long-term consequences for the actors themselves. Certain self- regarding duties are also relevant to assessing the behavior and attitudes of the ghetto poor: obligations to cultivate one’s basic capacities, to respect oneself as a moral person, or to avoid courses of action that would undermine one’s autonomy. While the ghetto poor are sometimes criticized on these grounds, and while such criticisms have led some to conclude that paternalistic or punitive responses are warranted, these questions, although important, are not what I want to focus on. My primary concern is to determine whether the deviant conduct and atti- tudes prevalent in the ghetto are unreasonable.40 That is, do these forms 40. For a discussion of the distinction between the rational and the reasonable in practical affairs, see Rawls, Political Liberalism, pp. 48–54. Also see T. M. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1998), pp. 189–94. A similar distinction, between cognitive-instrumental rationality and communicative rationality, is elaborated in Jürgen Habermas, The Theory of Communicative Action, Volume I: Reason and the Rationalization of Society (Boston, Mass.: Beacon Press, 1984), pp. 8–42. 143 Justice, Deviance, and the Dark Ghetto of deviance express an unwillingness to honor the fair terms of social cooperation that others accept and abide by? If the ghetto poor accept the benefits of the social scheme but violate the norms that make the scheme possible whenever doing so would advance their self-interests, then their nonconformity is opportunistic and may therefore appear unjustified to those complying with these norms. But, and this is the crucial point, whether their deviance is unreasonable depends on the justness of the overall social scheme. When people criticize the ghetto poor for failing to play by the rules that others honor, they are assuming, if only implicitly, that these rules are fair to all who play. As we have seen, however, the fairness of the scheme is open to doubt. Let us distinguish three possible assessments of the basic structure of U.S. society. On the first, we judge the United States to be a fully just society. In light of the observations summarized above, I do not regard this as a plausible view and so will not consider it further. On the second, we judge that there are some injustices that should be addressed but that the United States is not fundamentally unjust. On the third, we judge that the society is fundamentally unjust and will require radical reform to bring it in line with what basic justice demands. The question, then, is what obligations would the ghetto poor have if the second or third assessments were correct. To sharpen the question, I will invoke the familiar distinction between civic obligations and natural duties.41 Civic obligations are owed to those whom one is cooperating with to maintain a fair basic structure. They are the obligations that exist between citizens of a democratic polity as defined by the principles of justice that underpin their association. Civic obligations have binding normative force because of the contingent associational ties between citizens, that is, because of the formal or informal bonds that define a set of persons as a distinct people or nation. By contrast, natural duties are unconditionally binding, in that they hold between all persons regardless of whether they are fellow citizens or are bound by other institutional ties. Both civic obligations and natural duties are moral requirements. The key difference is that one has civic obligations qua citizen and natural duties qua moral person. 41. In elaborating this distinction I draw on Rawls’s distinction between social obliga- tions and natural duties, though perhaps not in the same way he intended. See Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 93–101. 144 Philosophy & Public Affairs Within a liberal framework, civic obligations are rooted in the political value of reciprocity. As a beneficiary of the primary goods afforded by the scheme of cooperation, each citizen has an obligation to fulfill the requirements of the basic institutions of his or her society when these institutions are just. Such reciprocity forbids the exploitation of fellow members of the society. Rawls rightly insists that one should not attempt to gain from the cooperative labors of others without doing one’s fair share. Just as important, he also correctly maintains that we do not have obligations to submit to unjust institutions, or at least not to institutions that exceed the limits of tolerable injustice. One difficulty we must face, then, is ascertaining just where to draw the line beyond which injustice becomes intolerable. Rawls does not provide such a standard. One standard we might use, though, is to live with unjust socioeconomic inequalities if the constitu- tional essentials are secure. For Rawls these essentials are the familiar basic rights of a liberal democratic regime—such as freedom of speech, conscience, assembly, and association; the right to vote and run for office; the right to due process and judicial fairness—and the political procedures that ensure democratic rule.42 The constitutional essentials also include freedom of movement, free choice of occupation, formal justice, and a social minimum that secures the basic material needs of all citizens. The constitutional essentials do not, however, include fair equality of opportunity (i.e., Rawls’s egalitarian interpretation of the equal opportunity principle); nor do they include the difference prin- ciple (i.e., his requirement that socioeconomic inequalities always work to the benefit of the least advantaged). A plausible rationale for using this standard for tolerable injustice is that it is most urgent to secure the constitutional essentials, given their indispensable role in creating social stability, and that reasonable people can disagree over how much socioeconomic inequality can be justified and over when existing institutional arrangements satisfy the principles of economic justice. The constitutional essentials establish the political legitimacy of a social order by publicly affirming the equal status of all citizens under the rule of law. If an otherwise unjust society met this standard, this would not mean that citizens should not agitate for more socioeconomic equality or use democratic processes or other legitimate 42. Rawls, Political Liberalism, pp. 227–30. 145 Justice, Deviance, and the Dark Ghetto political channels to fight for policies that would achieve a more egali- tarian basic structure. It would simply mean that their civic obligations were still fully binding and thus that they should fulfill these obligations as they work for a more just social arrangement. Assume for the moment that this proposed standard for tolerable injustice is currently met in the United States. Would it be reasonable to expect the ghetto poor to fulfill their civic obligations, even as they justifiably resent and protest continuing socioeconomic inequalities? Many U.S. citizens, regarding their society as imperfect but reasonably just, believe that the ghetto poor are not entitled to further public expenditures to improve their lives apart from, perhaps, some allow- ance for basic subsistence (e.g., food stamps). The attitudes, habits, and values of many of the black urban poor are widely thought to be in conflict with legitimate expectations for civic responsibility. Each citizen reasonably expects other citizens to fulfill their basic obligations as a citizen, to do their fair share in sustaining an institutional arrange- ment that works to everyone’s advantage. In particular, most U.S. citi- zens think that everyone, including the poor, should obey the law and that all able-bodied, working-age citizens (unless they are providing care for dependent relatives, are economically self-sufficient without working, or are engaged in full-time education or job training) should support themselves through legitimate work, even if that work is hard, low-paying, and unsatisfying. Thus, when the ghetto poor engage in criminal activity or refuse to work legitimate jobs, this is widely regarded as a failure of reciprocity on their part. This would be the wrong conclusion to draw, however.43 To see why, we first should remind ourselves that job opportunities for low-skilled 43. One way to deny at least the job aspect of this conclusion is to hold that a general work requirement is incompatible with liberal principles of justice, which must be neutral with respect to reasonable conceptions of the good and must not rely on a pre-political notion of moral desert. Criticizing the ghetto poor for not working could thus be regarded as illiberal, insofar as such criticism is premised on the idea that work is good for the worker or that only those who work are deserving of equal respect and concern. However, Stuart White, relying on a Rawlsian fair-play argument, makes a strong case that an obligation to work is a requirement of civic reciprocity, provided background conditions are just and that all who are able, including the wealthy, are expected to make a labor contribution to the common good. See his “Is Conditionality Illiberal?” in Welfare Reform and Political Theory, ed. Lawrence M. Mead and Christopher Beem (New York: Russell Sage Foundation, 2005), pp. 82–109. 146 Philosophy & Public Affairs workers are severely limited and the jobs that are available are often menial, dead-end service positions that pay wages too low to provide adequate economic security for a family. Now it might be replied that if the ghetto poor do not want to take these low-wage jobs they should develop their skills so that they can compete for better ones. This would mean graduating from high school and getting some post-secondary education, which too few from urban communities do. Indeed, it could be argued that even if one accepted the demanding principle “from each according to his or her ability, to each according to his or her needs,” it would be unreasonable—and not merely a violation of a self-regarding duty—for citizens to refuse to develop their abilities. As is widely known, however, the quality of education available to ghetto residents is generally so substandard that most cannot get a basic education there, let alone proper preparation for college.44 Moreover, because of high housing costs and racial discrimination, most are not able to move to neighborhoods where the schools are better. Furthermore, without sig- nificant public subsidies, those admitted to college usually lack sufficient resources to pay. This lack of equal educational opportunity, which in turn creates an unfair employment opportunity scheme, vitiates any obligation to work (should such a duty exist).45 No doubt many U.S. citizens criticize the poor on perfectionist grounds (e.g., on the grounds that desert requires a good work ethic), and some believe that all citizens, rich and poor, should work. One could also believe, however, as I think many Americans do, con- sidering their attitudes toward taxes on inheritance, that civic reciprocity requires, not work per se, but economic self-sufficiency: doing one’s part in upholding the scheme of cooperation means not forcing one’s fellow citizens to support you (unless of course you are unable to support yourself). To refuse to take care of yourself is widely regarded as imposing unfair burdens on others, say, through high taxes. So I will not assume that the critic of the ghetto poor is necessarily committed to a general civic obligation to work. 44. See Gary Orfield, Susan E. Eaton, and The Harvard Project on School Desegregation, Dismantling Desegregation: The Quiet Reversal of Brown v. Board of Education (New York: The New Press, 1996); and Jennifer L. Hochschild and Nathan Scovronick, The American Dream and the Public Schools (New York: Oxford University Press, 2004). 45. Again, I am not here assuming a general civic obligation to work. I am assuming that if such an obligation exists, each citizen should have a fair chance to compete for the desirable jobs and should be reasonably well compensated if he or she must choose from among undesirable employment options. It goes without saying that if jobs are not avail- able, the duty to work could not be binding. For contrasting views on whether there is a general obligation to work, see Lawrence C. Becker, “The Obligation to Work,” Ethics 91 147 Justice, Deviance, and the Dark Ghetto One might object that if the ghetto poor will not accept the jobs they qualify for and they refuse, or cannot afford, to continue their education, they should simply get by on whatever public welfare provisions that are available or on private aid, but without resorting to crime. Leaving aside for the moment the adequacy of current welfare benefits, we can appreciate the weakness in this objection if we keep in mind that the basic structure of any society will, in predictable and alterable ways, encourage certain desires and ambitions in its citizens; and lawmakers generally take into account how the overall incentive structure in society will be affected by the policies they enact. Any affluent, mass-consumer, capitalist society will encourage—indeed actively cultivate—the ambi- tion to live comfortably (if not get rich). This is, after all, how such econo- mies reproduce themselves: by creating continual mass desire for a wide range of consumer goods and services. If such a society only guarantees the constitutional essentials, however, without providing every citizen with a real opportunity to reach the goal of material comfort, then it is far from obvious that those who, because of lack of resources, are inhibited in this pursuit are being unreasonable when they choose crime as an alternative to subsistence living.46 As noted earlier, the core value underlying civic obligations is not a demanding egalitarian standard but simple reciprocity. The problem with using the constitutional essentials as the threshold for tolerable injustice is that it does not ensure genuine conditions of reciprocity for the most disadvantaged in the scheme. Each citizen should be secure in (1980): 35–49; and Philippe Van Parijs, “Why Surfers Should Be Fed: The Liberal Case for an Unconditional Basic Income,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 20 (1991): 101–31. Also see White, “Is Conditionality Illiberal?” 46. This is a different point from the one Jeffrie G. Murphy makes in “Marxism and Retribution,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 2 (1973): 217–43. Murphy argues that because capitalist societies encourage greed, envy, and selfishness, it would be unfair to punish poor citizens who, in acting on these socially sanctioned motives, commit crimes. As he says, “There is something perverse in applying principles that presuppose a sense of com- munity in a society which is structured to destroy genuine community” (p. 239). Although I am sympathetic to Murphy’s position, I am suggesting something less radical. My point is rather that affluent capitalist societies encourage the expectation that, with a reasonable degree of effort, any able-bodied person has a fair chance to live a life of relative material comfort. So if a person develops a life-plan based on this expectation yet the expectation is frustrated, not because of one’s lack of effort or ability, but because of inequities in the prevailing opportunity structure, one is not necessarily being unreasonable when one chooses illegitimate means to attain the expected standard of living. 148 Philosophy & Public Affairs the thought that he or she has equal standing within the scheme of cooperation. This means that the scheme should be organized so that it publicly conveys to each participant that his or her interests are just as important as any other participant’s. Perhaps fair equality of opportu- nity sets the bar too high for tolerable injustice.47 Still, in a society that does not ensure a wide distribution of wealth and that relies primarily on the market to distribute income, the standard for tolerable injustice should include an adequate opportunity to develop marketable skills. Those who are denied this can legitimately object that they are not being treated as equally valued members of a scheme of cooperation that is supposed to be mutually advantageous. It might be objected that the ghetto poor, despite their disadvantages, do have some chance, albeit not the same chance as other citizens, to acquire marketable skills and to find good jobs. Why is this not a suffi- cient sign that the system accords them equal concern? In any case, since the ghetto poor are not taking full advantage of the educational and employment opportunities that are available, how can their complaints about the intolerable injustice of the system be taken seriously? If substandard schools and poverty wages were unavoidable byproducts of social cooperation under modern conditions, then the first objection would have merit. However, with adjustments to the tax scheme, schools could be dramatically improved and low-wage earners could be brought up to a decent standard of living. The public and their elected representatives simply lack the commitment to justice to make the relevant adjustments. To the second objection I will simply note, for the moment, that one way to register one’s principled opposition to an unjust social system is to forgo chances to benefit from its unfair oppor- tunity structure.48 47. But perhaps not. For compelling considerations in favor of treating fair equality of opportunity as a constitutional essential, see Seana Valentine Shiffrin, “Race, Labor, and the Fair Equality of Opportunity Principle,” Fordham Law Review 72 (2004): 1643–75. 48. A similar point is suggested in G. A. Cohen, “The Structure of Proletarian Unfree- dom,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 12 (1983): 3–33. Cohen is responding to the anti-Marxist claim that the members of the working class are not forced to sell their labor power since any one of them, or almost any, could start their own small business and thus exit the proletarian class. He raises the important possibility that some workers, out of solidarity with the others, may object to taking an individual escape that is not part of a general liberation for all. Some members of the lumpen-proletarian ghetto poor might reasonably take a similar position. 149 Justice, Deviance, and the Dark Ghetto Not only does the constitutional-essentials standard for tolerable injustice allow too much inequality, but there is also reason to believe that not even this standard is currently met in the United States. Insti- tutional racism still exists across a number of major social institutions. There has in addition been a sharp reduction in welfare benefits and other social entitlements for the poor and unemployed (provisions that, arguably, were not adequate to begin with), and many are now forced to work for poverty wages to receive even these meager benefits (e.g., work- fare programs and the earned-income tax credit). These circumstances suggest that the constitutional essentials are not secure. Having the con- stitutional essentials codified in law is not sufficient to regard them as secure, as even a cursory knowledge of the history of the black struggle for equal citizenship should make clear. Civil rights laws must also be impartially and effectively enforced, so that all citizens, regardless of race or class background, can be confident that those with institutional power will respect their rights. The existence of the dark ghetto—with its combination of social stigma, extreme poverty, racial segregation (including poorly funded and segregated schools), and shocking incar- ceration rates—is simply incompatible with any meaningful form of reci- procity among free and equal citizens. The ghetto poor justifiably feel that by demanding that they work in miserable, low-paying jobs to secure their basic needs, more advantaged citizens are simply trying to keep their taxes from rising or, worse, attempting to exploit the labor of poor people. And when the poor refuse this unfair arrangement, they are either stigmatized as lazy and unde- serving or they are penalized for trying to gain income in the under- ground economy. From the standpoint of many ghetto residents, the social order lacks legitimacy.49 There appears to be a conspiracy to contain, exploit, and underdevelop the black urban poor, to deny them equal civic standing and punish them when they refuse to accommodate themselves to injustice. This appearance of conspiracy is, I suspect, the reflection of an underlying failure of the social scheme to fully embody the value of reciprocity. If we are to take equal citizenship seriously, then not only should we not attempt to gain from others’ labor without 49. This point is developed, within a broadly Rawlsian framework, in Howard McGary, “The Black Underclass and the Question of Values,” in The Underclass Question, ed. Bill E. Lawson (Philadelphia, Pa.: Temple University Press, 1992), pp. 57–70. 150 Philosophy & Public Affairs carrying our fair share of the burdens of maintaining the system of coop- eration, but we should not demand labor from those being deprived of their fair share of the benefits from the system. I would conjecture that in an affluent society with a recent history of overt racial exclusion, no reasonable standard for tolerable injustice is compatible with persistent ghetto conditions. If this conjecture is correct, then when the ghetto poor in the United States refuse to accept menial jobs or to respect the authority of the law qua law, they do not thereby violate the principle of reciprocity or shirk valid civic obligations.50 iv. oppression and the duty of justice However, even if a society is fundamentally unjust, i.e., it exceeds the limits of tolerable injustice, it does not follow that the ghetto poor have no moral duties to one another or to others. Only someone who holds that the cognitive-instrumental or utility-maximizing conception of reason is the only legitimate conception could think that an unjust social order rationally justifies a war of all against all, in which the only valid value systems are those of the gangster and hustler. The ghetto poor do have duties, natural duties, that are not defined by civic reciprocity and thus are not negated by the existence of an unjust social order.51 Among these is the duty not to be cruel. Each also has the duty to help the needy and vulnerable provided this is not too personally risky or costly. There is a duty to not cause unnecessary suffering. There is a duty of mutual respect: to show due respect for the moral personhood of others. There are also many other basic duties. Such duties are not sus- pended or void because one is oppressed. The existence of these duties 50. It is perhaps worth noting that Rawls insists that even within a reasonably just society there is a limit to how much injustice people should have to endure. In particular, he thinks that the burdens of injustice should, over time, be distributed more or less evenly across different sectors and groups in society, so that the weight of oppression does not fall mostly on any one group. Thus he says, “[T]he duty to comply [with reasonably just institutions] is problematic for permanent minorities that have suffered from injustice for many years” (Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 312). Even if the United States is reasonably just (according to some defensible standard for tolerable injustice), the burdens that the black urban poor are forced to carry, and the length of time they have had to carry them, might justify their refusal to comply with institutional demands; and if they do not, strictly speaking, provide a justification for such deviance, they almost certainly provide a legitimate excuse. 51. Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 98–100. 151 Justice, Deviance, and the Dark Ghetto makes some of the deviant attitudes and actions of the ghetto poor impermissible, not because they are forbidden by law but because they cannot be fully justified from a moral point of view. This means, at a minimum, that the reckless and gratuitous violence, the selfish indiffer- ence to others’ suffering, and the disregard for the humanity of one’s fellow human beings that are all too common in some poor urban neigh- borhoods should not be tolerated. There should also be special mindful- ness of how impressionable youth are and, in particular, of how observing the behavior of adults shapes a child’s moral development. Yet fulfillment of one’s natural duties to others may nevertheless be compatible with certain forms of crime. Taking the lives of others, except in self-defense or in defense of others, is hardly ever justified. However, taking the property of others, especially when these others are reason- ably well off, may be legitimate. Mugging someone at gunpoint may not show sufficient respect for the victim’s personhood, but shoplifting and other forms of theft might be justified. Given the hazards of participating in gang culture, recruiting children into gangs shows insufficient concern for the weak and vulnerable; yet given the advantages of con- certed group action, participating in gangs may be a defensible and effective means to secure needed income. There are also “victimless” crimes such as prostitution, welfare fraud, tax evasion, selling stolen goods, and other off-the-books transactions in the underground economy.52 There are of course many complex questions here about when coercion, threats, or deception may legitimately be used, and there is the salient question of which, if any, illegal narcotics may be sold to consenting adults without wronging them.53 I will not pursue these issues further, however. My goal is not to draw the precise line between permissible crimes and impermissible ones but only to offer reasons for thinking that the former set is not empty. I do, however, want to draw out the practical implications of one natural duty, the duty of justice. According to Rawls, this duty requires each individual (1) to support and comply with just institutions, and (2) where just institutions do not exist, to help to bring them about.54 No just 52. See Venkatesh, Off the Books. 53. For a helpful discussion of this latter issue, see Douglas N. Husak, “Liberal Neutral- ity, Autonomy, and Drug Prohibitions,” Philosophy & Public Affairs 29 (2000): 43–80. 54. Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 99. 152 Philosophy & Public Affairs societies or institutions could exist, at least not for very long, if individu- als did not work to create and sustain them. The very idea of social justice would seem to presuppose the duty of justice: no one can resent being treated unjustly and also consistently reject the duty of justice. Rawls argues for the validity of this duty by pointing out that the parties in the original position, seeing their common rational interest in the existence and stability of just institutions, would naturally agree that everyone should support and further such institutions. The duty of justice gives each person a strong moral reason to protest or resist unjust practices. The duty of self-respect, which is fulfilled by recognizing and affirming one’s equal moral worth as a person, also provides a reason to protest or resist injustice.55 But it differs from the duty of justice. One expresses self-respect by, for example, standing up for oneself when one has been treated unjustly, rather than meekly acquiescing. The duty of self-respect is a matter of defending one’s dignity in the face of injustice; the duty of justice is a matter of taking proactive steps to end injustice or to make the relevant institutions more just. The duty of self-respect is a self-regarding duty; the duty of justice is one owed to others. The duty of self-respect demands action from those who have been wronged; the duty of justice demands action regardless of whether one has been wronged. There have been important recent philosophical discussions about what relatively advantaged persons ought to do to eliminate or mitigate unjust circumstances.56 Yet there has been little attention to what obliga- tions to promote just institutions disadvantaged persons have. Some liberals are no doubt reluctant to discuss the moral obligations of the downtrodden out of an understandable distaste for “blaming the victim.” Moreover, they rightly maintain that indignation should be directed, first and foremost, toward the complacency of the well off, the “winners” in an unjust system. I want to insist, however, that the duty of justice also applies to the oppressed and in particular to the ghetto poor. Of course, it would be unreasonable to expect individuals to work to bring about a just society when doing so would be very dangerous or costly. Given the conditions in most ghettos, perhaps it is too much to ask 55. For a particularly insightful discussion of the duty of self-respect, see Boxill, Blacks and Social Justice, chap. 9. 56. See, for example, G. A. Cohen, If You’re an Egalitarian, How Come You’re So Rich? (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2000); and Liam Murphy, Moral Demands in Nonideal Theory (New York: Oxford University Press, 2000). 153 Justice, Deviance, and the Dark Ghetto of ghetto denizens that they make significant contributions to the cause of social justice. After all, many have more than they can handle just trying to meet their basic needs and maintain their dignity. Yet it is reasonable to expect the ghetto poor, in addition to fulfilling their other natural duties, to not take courses of action that would clearly exacerbate the injustices of the system or that would increase the burdens of injustice on those in ghetto communities or others similarly situated, at least not when these negative consequences could be avoided without too much self-sacrifice. Nor should they do things that would clearly make a just society more difficult to achieve, provided in refraining from such actions they can maintain their self-respect and meet their other basic needs. Expecting the ghetto poor to honor their natural duties, including the duty of justice, does not blame the victims. The ghetto poor should not be held responsible for the appalling social conditions that have been imposed on them because of the workings of an unjust social structure, but they should be held accountable for how they choose to respond to these conditions. Demanding this basic level of moral responsibility treats them as full moral persons and as political agents in their own right. Too often ghettos are viewed as “sick” communities, burdened with myriad pathologies, that the state-as-physician (or some suitable social service organization, such as a charity or church) must “heal.” Not only is this doctor-patient approach to the ghetto too often an expression of offensive paternalistic sentiments (which have well-known black elite noblesse oblige variants), but also it is the wrong paradigm when we are dealing with a social problem whose origin lies in systemic injustice. We all, whether we belong to dominant or subjugated groups, have a duty to help establish just social arrangements. Given that the injustices at issue are features of a system of social cooperation that we all, winners and losers, participate in, we should view the project to correct these injus- tices as a joint one, or at least it should be so viewed among those who want to live in a just society rather than to profit from an unjust one. Unfortunately, in light of the ill will, selfishness, and callous indiffer- ence of many of their fellow citizens, social justice might not be achiev- able unless the ghetto poor take on a good deal of the burden in reforming their society. As has so often been true in human history, the oppressed must play a large role—sometimes they have to be the principal agents—in ending the unjust practices they are subjected to. For example, black citizens had to play significant roles in abolishing slavery and Jim 154 Philosophy & Public Affairs Crow, despite having suffered most because of these systems of domina- tion. The fact that this is, in some sense, unfair is irrelevant. The duty of justice is not based on the principle of civic reciprocity. It is a duty each has qua moral person, not qua citizen. Therefore, one cannot opt out of this duty because one’s fellow citizens fail to fulfill it. Nor should one stop short of doing more than others in the struggle for justice on the ground that were these others to do their part one would not have to do as much (though the criticism of these others is no doubt warranted). Exactly how one should go about fulfilling the duty of justice, that is, which specific courses of action would satisfy it, will depend on which particular social circumstances one faces. In light of these circumstances, one must make an assessment of how best to contribute to improving things. This assess- ment will necessarily involve determining just how much assistance one can realistically expect from others and how best to enlist this aid. When viewed from this vantage point, ghetto residents should think carefully about how they respond to the injustices of the social order and consider whether the forms of deviance they sometimes engage in are ultimately obstacles to effecting positive social change. Many people claim that they would be willing to help the poor pro- vided the poor would make an honest effort to help themselves by, say, working, getting an education, and staying out of jail. More advantaged citizens do not want to feel that they are being taken advantage of, and they often suspect that the urban poor lag behind because they lack the necessary work ethic. So one might think that, if not from prudential motives then from the duty of justice, the ghetto poor should avoid deviant behavior and take greater responsibility for helping themselves, as this would assure their fellow citizens that they are not being exploited and thereby encourage them to do something about improving the con- ditions in the ghetto.57 However, if the ghetto poor have compelling reasons to think that they are not being treated as equal citizens (say, because a tolerable level of injustice has been exceeded and they are being forced to carry the bulk of the burdensome consequences of this injustice), then they should be the ones worried about being hustled. Given rising inequality and the worsening of the ghetto/prison complex, which show no signs of abating, they have every reason to believe that 57. This argument is suggested in Jennifer L. Hochschild, “The Politics of the Estranged Poor,” Ethics 101 (1991): 560–78. 155 Justice, Deviance, and the Dark Ghetto their interests are not being given equal consideration. Why should they think that if they were only to behave better things would change? More- over, to ask them to demonstrate their worthiness for assistance that they are entitled to as a matter of justice would add insult to injury. The suggestion that the ghetto poor “prove themselves” before their compa- triots offer help fails to appreciate that acquiescing to injustice is simply incompatible with the maintenance of self-respect. v. from spontaneous defiance to political resistance One of the ways that the ghetto poor have sometimes responded to their plight is to engage in spontaneous rebellion. This may take the form of openly transgressing conventional norms, expressing contempt for authority, desecrating revered symbols, pilfering from employers or state institutions, vandalizing public and private property, or disrupting public events.58 Spontaneous rebellion reaches its apotheosis in the urban riot, where looting, mass destruction of property, and brutal vio- lence are on public display. When legitimate avenues for political action fail to produce results or are closed off, such public unrest can seem to be the only power the ghetto poor can wield collectively that has a chance of garnering concessions from the state.59 Many of these acts of defiance, though perhaps politically ineffective, may be necessary for the ghetto poor to maintain their self-respect. If nothing else, such actions can be cathartic and can help the oppressed to keep from turning on each other as they seek an outlet for their justified anger. Yet not all expressions of rebellion are aimed at protest- ing or changing the social order. Some ostensible defiance, on closer scrutiny, reveals itself to be no more than a desire to exploit the system opportunistically, as when demagogues take advantage of the anger of the poor to gain personal power or when gangsters and hustlers take advantage of others’ desperation merely for their own gain—capitalism by other means, as it were. What may have begun as principled 58. See Robin D. G. Kelley, Race Rebels: Culture, Politics, and the Black Working Class (New York: Free Press, 1996). 59. See Frances Fox Piven and Richard A. Cloward, Poor People’s Movements: Why They Succeed, How They Fail (New York: Vintage, 1979), pp. 18–23. For insightful reflections on the significance of a recent urban riot, see the essays in Reading Rodney King/Reading Urban Uprising, ed. Robert Gooding-Williams (New York: Routledge, 1993). 156 Philosophy & Public Affairs resistance can become, because of encroaching cynicism, “life-is-unfair” resignation. Some juvenile deviance is little more than adolescent rebel- lion unchecked by proper adult supervision. The key practical question, of course, is how, if at all, can this general impulse toward rebellion in U.S. ghettos be transformed into enduring and effective forms of political resistance. I will not pretend to have the answer to this difficult question. I would, however, like to briefly outline what kinds of moral criticism of the ghetto poor might be appropriate in light of the aim of cultivating constructive forms of resistance, thus giving some concrete content to the abstract duty of justice. Rawls distinguishes two different ways a society might be unjust.60 The first way is when the publicly recognized standards for judging the justice of the basic structure are sound but the institutional arrangement of the society fails to satisfy these standards. In this case, the society fails to live up to its own professed ideals, ideals that are worthy of public recognition. Alternatively, social arrangements may fit the prevailing conception of justice in the society or the political views of the ruling elite but neverthe- less be unjust. In this case, the dominant conception of justice is an ideology, a set of widely held beliefs and implicit assumptions that legiti- mates and thereby helps to sustain an oppressive regime.61 If the first situation obtains, the political opposition may be able to appeal to their fellow citizens’ sense of justice, highlighting the gap between ideals and practice. Here, nonviolent civil disobedience, public demonstrations, or other forms of mass protest that attempt to arouse the public’s sense of moral outrage may be productive. Since the era of New World slavery, the dominant tradition in African American activism, from Frederick Douglass to Martin Luther King, Jr., has generally taken this approach. However, if the society is stabilized by a deeply flawed conception of justice, for example one that serves the narrow interests of corporate and political elites, then more drastic or unconventional mea- sures may be warranted. Given a dominant ideology that advances a distorted view of what justice demands and that is widely endorsed because of narrow self-interests or illegitimate group interests, it might 60. Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 308–10. 61. For a more developed account of when a socially accepted set of beliefs constitutes an ideology, with a particular focus on racial ideology, see my “Ideology, Racism, and Critical Social Theory.” 157 Justice, Deviance, and the Dark Ghetto not be sufficient to appeal to the majority’s sense of justice. Moral suasion and electoral politics may simply not be enough. Black nation- alists, from Martin Delany to Malcolm X, have taken exactly this position with respect to the United States, regarding this society as a deeply racist and plutocratic social order. Those who oppose such a regime would have to develop a militant social movement that pushes the society in a more progressive direction, not “by any means necessary” but perhaps through means widely, though mistakenly, regarded as unjus- tified. The black urban poor have often been attracted to such black nationalist doctrines.62 Of course this contrast between the two ways a regime can be unjust, although analytically useful, is too stark for practical purposes. Some aspects of an overall social arrangement (for instance, its educational and economic institutions) may be regulated by a corrupt ideology, while other parts (say, its constitution or basic political organization) may be just or diverge from reasonable public standards of justice. Indeed, con- trary to the view of some black radicals (who believe that liberal political thought and practice is rotten to the core), this mixed assessment may be the one most applicable to post–civil rights America, as the civil rights movement did, I believe, help to make blacks’ constitutional rights con- siderably more meaningful. Thus, the political resistance, even if it takes a militant form, must take into account the reasonableness of existing aspects of the social scheme and choose measures of opposition accord- ingly.63 To be sure, militant leaders must be willing to take political mea- sures that some might find unacceptable if overcoming serious injustices requires these tactics. And political insurgency aimed at overthrowing an oppressive regime is sometimes justified. However, given the proven difficulty of establishing and maintaining just institutions in the modern 62. There is a variant of this point of view that would appear to have traction in some urban black communities. On this alternative view, the United States is thoroughly corrupt and cannot be redeemed. Given that mass emigration would be impossible for the poor, the only viable option is to build self-reliant ghetto communities without any expectation that justice will someday prevail throughout the whole of the society. Even if this pessimis- tic prognosis were correct (although I do not believe it is or, rather, hope it is not), the duty of justice would still need to be honored in this black nation within a nation. However, I will not explore the practical implication of the duty in this context. For my response to this brand of black nationalism, see my We Who Are Dark: The Philosophical Foundations of Black Solidarity (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2005), chaps. 3–4. 63. I owe this point to Tim Scanlon. 158 Philosophy & Public Affairs world, preserving the reasonably just components of an overall unjust system while pushing insistently for broader reforms may ultimately be a better strategy than abrupt radical reconstruction. Moreover, grassroots organizing and populist collective action would still require some measure of public order to be effective, and so the political institutions currently in place—with their provisions protecting freedom of speech, association, and assembly—could prove useful, their “superstructural” character notwithstanding. These are difficult and complex questions of political practice that theory can only do so much to illuminate. Yet no matter what form such opposition should take, the ghetto poor should be included in the resis- tance effort. In fulfilling the duty of justice, ghetto residents will need to build bonds of political solidarity with each other and with progressive allies.64 Such solidarity requires not only shared political values and the common goal of ending ghetto conditions but also a sense of compas- sion for those similarly oppressed. It calls for special concern, a willing- ness to help the most disadvantaged among you when you can. Solidarity demands loyalty to those you are working together with to change things for the better. Perhaps most important, it requires a sense of mutual trust, without which collective action cannot occur. If such solidarity is to form and be sustained, however, an outlaw subculture cannot reign in the ghetto. A climate of fear and suspicion erodes any chance of developing mutual trust. It undermines empathy and compassion because those who appear to be in need might in fact be trying to exploit you, or worse. If loyalty to one’s gang trumps all other loyalties or leads one to disregard the legitimate interests of those outside the gang, then no broader form of loyalty in ghetto communities can take shape, let alone stable forms of political organization. This means that the gangster and hustler ethics, qua value system, must be repudiated. I am not, however, suggesting that the ghetto poor are never justified in engaging in street crime. On the contrary, lacking acceptable alternatives, crime may be necessary to meet one’s needs or the needs of others. Nor am I saying that one should never make use of the criminal repertoire of 64. I describe the general requirements of political solidarity in We Who Are Dark, pp. 67–71. For a helpful discussion of what duties the members of oppressed groups have to each other, see Michael Walzer, “The Obligations of Oppressed Minorities,” in his Obliga- tions: Essays on Disobedience, War, and Citizenship (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1970), pp. 46–70. 159 Justice, Deviance, and the Dark Ghetto gangsters and hustlers—street capital—to secure necessary income. The political economy of the underground may require these tactics. What I am suggesting is that the techniques of the gangster and hustler should not be used merely to gain power, status, or riches; that one should not allow these practices to constitute one’s enduring social identity; and that one should be careful not to let the use of these tactics corrupt one’s character. Gangsterism and hustling must not be regarded as vocations, but as survival tactics, means of self-defense, or expressions of justified rebellion. Moreover, if street capital is to be converted into political capital in a resistance movement, then ghetto rebellion should not be merely opportunistic or cathartic but, whenever possible, should publicly register dissent. It is crucial, given the duty of justice and on grounds of self-respect, that the ghetto poor make manifest their principled dissat- isfaction with the existing social order, either through politically moti- vated modes of deviance or in some other recognizable way. vi. conclusion The urban poor should not be demonized, stigmatized, or otherwise dehumanized, just as surely as they should not be romanticized. Yet it would be a mistake to think that they should never be morally criticized. Moral criticism can be appropriate even when the targeted behavior and attitudes have been shaped and encouraged by unjust conditions and even when those subjected to criticism are not responsible for the fact that these conditions exist. Such criticism is one way for the members of oppressed groups to hold one another accountable and to create mean- ingful bonds of solidarity, and can even be offered by sympathetic out- siders seeking to build political alliances. But there are legitimate and constructive forms of moral criticism and illegitimate and self-serving forms. By appreciating how the lack of justice in a basic structure affects what obligations citizens have, we might better distinguish the two types of criticism, and in the process invite the kind of joint action needed to establish and maintain justice. 160 Philosophy & Public Affairs work_3mxu6wn6hzbknkw7oo5lkg6nt4 ---- A gray area of environmental justice. e e~~~ approved by the end of January 1995. If the program is approved, Scripps would immediately begin installing the speakers, and transmissions could begin that spring, Rogers said. A Move for the Better A change in where they live may change the outcome of a second pregnancy for women whose first child was born with a birth defect, according to a recent study published in the July 7 New England Journal ofMedicine. The odds of having a second child with a birth defect are small to begin with- about 2.2% in the Norwegian sample. However, the study, conducted by epi- demiologists Rolv Terje and Rolv Skjaerven in Norway and Allen Wilcox at the NIEHS, revealed that among women who had given birth to one baby with a defect, those who continued to live in the same town had almost 12 times the risk of giving birth to a second baby with the same defect. However, if these women moved to a new town, the risk dropped to five times the normal risk. The study also showed a slightly increased risk of deliver- ing a second child with a different defect from the first for women who remained in the same town. The study examined birth records of first and second infants born to almost 400,000 women in Norway between 1967 and 1989. Twenty-three categories of iso- lated defects and a category of multiple defects including, for example, cleft lip and palate, limb defects, genital defects, anen- cephaly, respiratory system defects, and central nervous system defects were studied. One surprising finding of the study is that moving to a new town correlated with a decreased risk of birth defects more than the second child being fathered by a differ- ent man. With a different father the risk of defects in the second child fell to 7.3. The authors say the study does not cast light on any causes for decreased risk, but when you move, said Wilcox, "you've changed some things: where you work, the house you live in...." Wilcox said that the study is more promising for guiding future research rather than for suggesting preven- tive measures. The researchers concluded that there is strong indirect evidence that environmental factors contribute to the familial risk of birth defects and that "important environmental teratogens have yet to be discovered." A Gray Area of Environmental Justice The issue of environmental justice is hard- ly black and white, especially in the realm Risk of similar and dissimilar birth defects in second infants of mothers with an affected first infant Second infant Defect in Similar defect Dissimilar defect first infant No. at risk Observed Expected Relative risk Observed Expected Relative risk Clubfoot 2784 100 14.7 7.3 59 42.0 1.4 Genital defect 1447 25 5.1 4.9 35 24.2 1.5 Limb defect 957 25 2.2 11.3 41 17.1 2.4 Cardiac defect 567 6 1.0 6.0 11 10.5 1.1 Total cleft lip 436 18 0.6 31.4 10 8.2 1.2 Isolated cleft palate 144 3 0.1 44.5 2 2.9 0.7 All combined 9192 201 26.4 7.6 249 164.6 1.5 Effect of a change in municipality or partner on the risk of a birth defect in the second infant similar to the defect in the first infant Similar birth defect in second infant Mothers with affected Mothers with normal first infants first infants Partner Municipality Cases Total Cases Total Relative Risk Same Same 115 4200 454 192,990 11.6 Same Different 41 2332 310 89,588 5.1 Different Same 16 985 99 44,196 7.3 Different Different 10 749 78 28,861 4.9 Source: Lie et al., NewEngland Joumal ofMedicine (vol. 331, p. 3). of research. Several studies surfaced in the late 1970s and 1980s providing evidence that polluting and waste facilities are more likely to be located in low-income and minority neighborhoods. This information has prompted widespread political action, but the methodologies used in these stud- ies are now being challenged. President Clinton issued an executive order on environmental justice, and Con- gress is also focusing on this issue, debating several bills that would guarantee environ- mental equity. But some researchers are questioning whether such political atten- tion to the issue is warranted. Two recent studies cast doubt on the empirical evi- dence supporting the arguments of envi- ronmental justice advocates. One of the studies, conducted at the Center for the Study of American Business at Washington University, examined envi- ronmental justice policy. "Our study is an overview of the issue from a policy per- spective," said Christopher Boerner, who worked with Thomas Lambert on the study. Their findings indicate that further research should be conducted on the issue. Boerner and Lambert, research interns at the center, analyzed the studies that pro- vide evidence of environmental racism and detected several flaws in the research. These included inadequacies in how mi- nority communities were defined and in population densities. The researchers said that defining minority communities as areas where the percentage of nonwhite residents exceeds the percentage of minori- ties in the entire population means that a community could be considered minority even if the majority of its residents are white. They also pointed out that most of the studies are based on ZIP-code data, which are not necessarily accurate when examined on a smaller geographic unit. Boerner and Lambert also argued that environmental justice studies imply rather than state actual risks posed by polluting and waste facilities since there is a lack of significant scientific data linking negative health effects with proximity to polluting and waste facilities. And finally, the study says that the research on environmental justice fails to establish that discriminatory siting and permitting practices caused cur- rent environmental inequities. The studies identify current economic and race charac- teristics of communities located around industrial and waste facilities, but they do not consider community conditions when the facilities were sited. Boerner and Lambert's research sup- ports one of their major concerns in regard to environmental justice: that policymakers may be acting too quickly on a subject that needs further research and evaluation. Boerner and Lambert also examined alternative ways of approaching environ- mental justice as an issue, as opposed to current suggested solutions. Most of these current remedies include legislation that would prohibit or discourage construction of polluting and waste facilities in certain low-income and minority neighborhoods. Boerner and Lambert recommended that policymakers explore remedies such as compensation approaches, in which those Volume 102, Number 10, October 1994 817 M- who share the benefits of the undesirable facility provide compensation to those who host the facility. The compensation could be in the form of direct payment to indi- viduals in the community, or through investments to improve the community. Boerner and Lambert also detailed benefits that communities could reap by support- ing the construction of polluting and waste facilities in their areas. Among these are the economic benefits a facility could bring to a disadvantaged neighborhood, such as the creation of jobs. This type of compensa- tion approach would allow communities to be involved in the negotiating process. Early results of an ongoing empirical study at the University of Massachusetts also cast doubt on claims that hazardous waste facilities are more likely to be located in low-income and minority neighbor- hoods. The researchers, Douglas Anderton and Andy Anderson, both sociology pro- fessors, released a preliminary study reveal- ing that commercial, off-site treatment, storage, and disposal facilities (TSDFs) are actually more likely to be located in white, working-class, industrial neighborhoods. The two-year study examined census bureau tracts, groupings of 4,000 people, rather than ZIP-code data, which had been used in many of the previous studies. Tracts containing commercial hazardous waste TSDFs were compared to tracts without TSDFs. The researchers had expected to find results similar to previous studies on envi-. ronmental justice. "We were all pretty sur- prised, including the waste industry," Anderton said. "In retrospect we shouldn't have been, because what we found was that these facilities were not much different than any other industrial facilities." They found that the neighborhoods surrounding TSDFs were made up of white, working-class peo- ple, similar to most communities located around other types of industrial facilities. The study has been criticized by envi- ronmental justice advocates because the pre-1990 census tract data that was ana- lyzed excludes rural areas. They claim that if rural areas were assessed, the results could be different. However, Anderton says ongoing research involves 1990 census data that includes rural areas, and the results appear to be similar. Anderton and Anderson do admit that there are limitations to this study. For example, only commercial, off-site TSDFs were studied; Superfund sites, closed TSDFs, and on-site storage were excluded. They also cited other sources of environ- mental risk not studied that could unfairly burden minority and poor populations, including lead paint, soil contamination, and air pollution. "Some of the limitations of this research should be noted so the results of this particular study will not be used to undermine the general cause of environ- mental justice and equity," the authors said. They summarized the study by say- ing, "a great deal of work remains to be done." Anderton said they will continue to research the issue, and future studies will include Toxic Release Inventory data, Superfund sites, comparisons of public and private facilities, and analyses of how sites change over time. A Nice Cup of Tea Animal studies prove it. Folklore heralds it. And now the first large human study shows that green tea may be more than just an aromatic brew loved by millions of Asians who claim it purifies the body. A report published in the June issue of the Journal ofthe National Cancer Institute concluded that green tea is associated with a reduced rate of esophageal cancer in resi- dents of Shanghai. Studying 1552 healthy people and 902 others who had esophageal cancer, NCI researchers found the risk of contracting this cancer was reduced by 57% for men and 60% for women who didn't smoke or drink alcohol but who consumed lots of green tea. The researchers undertook the study because of compelling animal experiments that demonstrated green tea reduces the incidence of cancer and even the growth rate of tumors. Tea is among the most widely consumed beverages in the world, and a finding that 20% of that tea, an unfermented green, naturally protects against cancer would be good public health news. The report comes on the heels of a smattering of studies worldwide that sug- gest green tea has a myriad of benefits. In Japan, scientists have found that green tea lowers rates of cancers of the lung, skin, and stomach, and even reduces cholesterol. But no one is yet ready to say that green tea protects humans against any dis- ease, including cancer. The NCI's lead tea investigator, epidemiologist Joseph McLaughlin, cautions that no conclusions can yet be made. "This is the first study that shows an association, but as to whether green tea does definitively protect against esophageal cancer, I can't say." The problem is that although at least 100 studies have been published in the last two years, mostly in Asia, there are too few substantive case-control studies, says McLaughlin. The NCI survey is the largest to date, "but further investigations are defi- nitely needed," he said. Chung Yang, a biochemist and profes- sor at Rutgers University, said that recent reports of the effect of tea on human health have been "mixed; innately contro- versial." Yang said that one-fourth of the studies argue for a protective effect, one- fourth find tea increases health risks, and one-half of the studies found no correla- tion between consumption and disease. And although the Shanghai study "is inter- esting and encouraging," Yang said that it did not present any clear conclusions. On the other hand, animal data testing the effect of both black and green tea on cancer has shown a consistent benefit, said Yang, who has had a role in many of those t Reading tea leaves. Scientists studying green tea believe it may help ensure a healthier future. Reading tea leaves. Scientists studying green tea believe it may help ensure a healthier future. 818 Environmental Health Perspectives work_3oovbknv25gf5lwpplf6qjtxgm ---- Eric Brandstedt Non-ideal climate justice Article (Accepted version) (Refereed) Original citation: Brandstedt, Eric (2017) Non-ideal climate justice. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy. pp. 1-14. ISSN 1369-8230 DOI: 10.1080/13698230.2017.1334439 © 2017 Informa UK Limited This version available at: http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/83178/ Available in LSE Research Online: July 2017 LSE has developed LSE Research Online so that users may access research output of the School. Copyright © and Moral Rights for the papers on this site are retained by the individual authors and/or other copyright owners. Users may download and/or print one copy of any article(s) in LSE Research Online to facilitate their private study or for non-commercial research. You may not engage in further distribution of the material or use it for any profit-making activities or any commercial gain. You may freely distribute the URL (http://eprints.lse.ac.uk) of the LSE Research Online website. This document is the author’s final accepted version of the journal article. There may be differences between this version and the published version. You are advised to consult the publisher’s version if you wish to cite from it. http://www.tandfonline.com/toc/fcri20/current http://www.tandfonline.com/toc/fcri20/current http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/13698230.2017.1334439 https://informa.com/ http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/83178/ 1 Review Article: Non-Ideal Climate Justice Eric Brandstedt Centre for Philosophy of Natural and Social Science (CPNSS), London School of Economics and Political Science, London, UK Postal address: CPNSS, Lakatos Building, London School of Economics and Political Science, Houghton Street, London, WC2A 2AE Email corresponding author: e.brandstedt@lse.ac.uk This is an accepted manuscript of an article published by Taylor & Francis in Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy on 01/06/17, available at http://www.tandfonline.com/doi/full/10.1080/13698230.2017.1334439 mailto:e.brandstedt@lse.ac.uk 2 Review Article: Non-Ideal Climate Justice Eric Brandstedt* Centre for Philosophy of Natural and Social Science (CPNSS), London School of Economics and Political Science, London, UK Based on three recently published books on climate justice, this article reviews the field of climate ethics in light of developments of international climate politics. The central problem addressed is how idealised normative theories can be relevant to the political process of negotiating a just distribution of the costs and benefits of mitigating climate change. I distinguish three possible responses, that is, three kinds of non-ideal theories of climate justice: focused on (1) the injustice of some agents not doing their part; (2) the policy process and aiming to be realistic; and (3) grievances related to the transition to a clean-energy economy. The methodological discussion underpinning each response is innovative and should be of interest more generally, even though it is still underdeveloped. The practical upshot, however, is unclear: even non-ideal climate justice may be too disconnected from the fast-moving and messy climate circus. Keywords: non-ideal theory, climate injustice, transitional climate justice, realistic climate justice, noncompliance, climate justice Henry Shue, Climate justice: vulnerability and protection. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014. Pp. 353. ISBN 978-0-19-871370-8. Clare Heyward and Dominic Roser, eds., Climate justice in a non-ideal world. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016. Pp. 323. ISBN 978-0-19-874404-7. Dominic Roser and Christian Seidel, Climate justice: an introduction. Abingdon, Oxon: Routledge, 2017. Pp. 229. ISBN13: 978-1-138-84527-5. I. Introduction Climate change already causes great economic losses, extreme hardship and premature death by inducing droughts, crop failures, and other detrimental effects. If nothing is done, it will get worse: extreme weather events will become more frequent, and in the worst-case scenario, present an existential threat. To mitigate such dangers the nation states of the world have accepted to ‘[hold] the increase in global average temperature to well below 2°C above pre- industrial levels and [to pursue] efforts to limit the temperature increase to 1.5°C above pre- industrial levels’, as part of the Paris Agreement (UNFCCC 2015, Art. 2.1). They have also 3 approved that meeting this goal requires net-zero emissions of greenhouse gases (GHGs) in the second half of this century. The aforementioned agreement is effectively a normative decision about the right balance of probability-weighted costs and benefits of measures to reduce emissions and those of other policy objectives, including how much to spend on adaptation to unmitigated climate change. It furthermore has normative implications in the sense that it raises questions about how to meet the target, and who should do what, and how fast it should be done. Transitioning to a clean-energy economy will entail both large costs and large non-climate benefits that should be fairly distributed. Ideally, normative theory should be relevant to answering such questions. A theory of climate justice, that is, a set of principles for distributing the goods and burdens of climate change mitigation, could function as an aspirational goal for the just transformation of the current fossil fuel economy. But in the current state of climate politics it is easy to despair – also about normative theory. Although the Paris Agreement may turn things around, climate politics has been and is still to a large extent in a deadlock. Many actors dig in their heels: refuse to act fairly, act as first mover, or even act at all. In this situation, it is unclear what impact philosophical analyses, however sophisticated, could have. What Brian Barry (2003, p. 498) wrote in a different context rings true here: ‘whether we make the demands of justice more or less stringent, it is going to demand more than is likely to get done in the foreseeable future’. In response to such worries, one may seek resort in what is known as ‘non-ideal theory’. Perhaps climate ethicists – that is, normative theorists working on climate change – have been too preoccupied with developing ideal theories, and should now focus their efforts on more practically relevant tasks. Such an idea can be distinguished in the collected works Climate Justice: Vulnerability and Protection (2014) that Henry Shue recently has put together. Similarly, a whole third of Dominic Roser and Christian Seidel’s just published Climate Justice: An Introduction (2017) is devoted to questions about how ethical ideals can and should be put to political practice. Moreover, as the title gives away, it is centrally featured in the anthology Climate Justice in a Non-Ideal World (2016) that Clare Heyward and Dominic Roser have edited. It has also been the topic of some journal articles: Hohl and Roser (2011), Maltais (2013, 2014), Caney (2005, 2016a), Gajevic Sayegh (2016). In this article, I will review the discussion of non-ideal climate justice with the primary aim of clarifying the central concepts therein. This is pertinent because the idea of non-ideal theory – and its opposite, ideal theory – is far from clear. I will thus begin by disambiguating it and highlighting the different ways it has been put to use in the discussion of climate justice. Thereby, I also hope to contribute to an assessment of the role of climate ethics in relation to climate politics. II. Disambiguating the Distinction I should first set aside a common usage of ‘non-ideal’ in discussions of climate justice. That is, when it is to signify the difficult nature of the problem; or, in the words of Aaron Maltais (2013, p. 598), the ‘extremely unfavourable conditions for effective climate politics’. Although what is referred to here must be accounted in the implementation and possibly even justification of 4 climate justice, the expression should not be confused with that of non-ideal theory. Also note that this expression can be confusing also after this clarification. Seeing that the dictionary definition of ‘non-ideal’ is ‘real’, all real-world conditions, however difficult or easy to overcome, are non-ideal in this sense. So, if one wants to isolate the specific character of climate politics, it is better to use another term, such as ‘difficult’, ‘problematic’, or perhaps ‘wicked’. From here on, I will reserve ‘non-ideal’ to name a particular kind of normative theory, and examine three different interpretations of it in the climate justice discussion, concerned with partial compliance (in section III), realism (in section IV), and transition (in section V), respectively. The tripartite structure comes from the three senses of the distinction between ideal and non-ideal theory that Laura Valentini (2012) has pointed out. That is, first, as a distinction between full and partial compliance with normative principles theorised.1 One can either work out normative principles on the assumption that all agents can and will comply to the extent that is possible and reasonable for them to do so, or on the assumption that there is or will be some noncompliance, that is, some agents not doing what they should. Non-ideal theory, in this sense, concerns how to respond to injustice. Secondly, it has been understood as a distinction between more utopian and more realistic normative theories. There is a question about to what extent various feasibility constraints or facts should be taken into account in normative theorising. Thirdly, it has been understood as the difference between focusing on the end-state of a perfectly just society, or on transitional concerns about improvements from the status quo. III. Dealing with Climate Injustice The partial compliance interpretation is probably the most common one among climate ethicists (see Caney 2005, 2016a, 2016b, Hohl and Roser 2011, Shue 2014, ch. 15, Roser and Seidel 2017, ch. 17). And not without reason: The apparent disregard for climate change that characterises world politics suggests that questions about how to deal with climate injustice are central. It seems less relevant to try and work out the precise details of principles of climate justice when agents today cannot plausibly be said to comply with any, however modest, requirements of justice. Furthermore, as Shue (2014, ch. 9) argues, the commonly discussed ideal principles perhaps anyhow converge on the same policy prescriptions. What is important to note, then, is that this raises new and distinct ethical considerations. Questions about how to deal with non-compliers cannot be swept aside as merely practical matters; they are of moral significance and in need of a separate, non-ideal theory of climate justice. As Simon Caney (2016a, p. 12) notes, the existence of noncompliance implies a shortfall of justice, which leads to the question: ‘Where should the shortfall lie?’ In order to determine this and to thus develop a non-ideal theory of climate justice, Caney (2016a) proposes a three-step methodology. The first step is to list possible responses to noncompliance. Note that these are often discussed in terms of the fairness of demanding of compliers to ‘take up the slack’ of non- compliers. One response is that it would be unfair because fairness determines invariable shares. But one may also argue that the existence of noncompliance does affect the ideally fair distribution of responsibility: either, as some state representatives less plausibly have claimed2, 5 by freeing compliers from responsibility (as it is conditional on some level of compliance), or by increasing responsibility, such that, compliers are now required to do even more (see e.g. Caney 2005, pp. 767-772). Sabine Hohl and Dominic Roser (2011) suggest another possibility: that although it would be unfair to demand of compliers to do more than their fair share, they are still so required because each additional burden3 shouldered makes it less likely that human rights are violated as a result of climate change. Roser and Seidel (2017, pp. 170-171) similarly concede the unfairness of compliers having to shoulder residual burdens, but argue that it must be balanced against a much worse injustice, namely that of allowing great harm being inflicted on third parties (i.e. the effects of climate change on future people). Caney (2016b) expands and develops the standard set of responses, adding, among other things, the possibility of relaxing moral side-constraints on action and of changing the incentive structure to increase future compliance. The second step responds to the need to evaluate and choose between the possible responses. Like many in the general discussion (e.g. Rawls 1999, p. 90; cf. Simmons 2010), Caney (2016a) argues that this must be met with ideal theory. Non-ideal theory presupposes ideal theory: the aim of the former is to approximate the latter. There are two things to note here. First, by implication, it is not enough to just assume (as I did above) that present agents have not complied with their responsibilities on most theories of justice; the evaluation of appropriate responses depends on a more specified ideal theory. The second thing is that, at least for Caney, there seems to be a strict partitioning between ideal and non-ideal theory. As far as the development of the latter goes, ideal principles are not revisable, but insensitive to facts and intuitions related to the application. Non-ideal theorising is thus not a matter of testing ideals against reality and possibly adjusting them accordingly. It is rather applying an independently justified theory of justice. The aim is to deal with climate injustices in ways conducive to the ultimate objective of an ideal theory. It is always the ideals prescribed that should inform the treatment of noncompliance: agents must ask themselves whether a particular course of action will be an ethically acceptable (as judged by the ideal), efficient and effective step towards the ideal. There can be no compromising of the ideal. In the third step of his account of non-ideal climate justice, Caney argues that one must attend to what is (politically) feasible for differently positioned agents, such as governments, firms, and individuals. Depending on the individual agent’s action space, different actions will be called for by the non-ideal theory of climate justice. The government of a well-positioned and affluent nation state will need to take actions different from those of a potential victim of climate change, such as an individual farmer in a developing country. The former may need to take on extra mitigation burdens or help finance an institutional framework to encourage future compliance (what Caney calls ‘Changing the Incentives Structure’). The latter may be permitted certain acts of civil disobedience, for instance, to take possession of certain low-carbon technology (‘Burden Shifting II’). These facts are relevant to determining what is an efficient and effective step towards the ideal. So although ultimate principles of justice are abstracted away from the facts on the ground, on Caney’s theory, their application is not. Thus, although all considered agents are required to comply with one and the same ideal theory, different agents may be required to do different things in response to noncompliance. How and why will their obligations differ? The answer is given by ideal theory.4 If it prescribes, say, that all agents should enjoy comparable opportunities to lead a good life, then those with fewer opportunities should shoulder fewer additional burdens, and vice versa. Residual 6 responsibility would, accordingly, be distributed in accordance with ability to take on additional burdens, subtracting what is needed to lead a good life. Given the opening for a plurality of different ideal theories, each with their distinct non-ideal auxiliaries, it is a striking fact that climate ethicists generally support some such cosmopolitan egalitarianism coupled with some such ability-based principle for residual responsibility.5 One can also challenge the premises of the take-up-the-slack-understanding of partial compliance theory. Caney’s non-ideal theory, in a way, does so by drawing on the multidimensional and dynamic character of real-life decisions.6 He rightly notes that the action space is variable, which enables positive or negative incentive effects: additional burdens carried by compliers can make it more or less likely that non-compliers will come to comply too. But it is even clearer with Aaron Maltais (2014), who argues that the problem is more fundamental than what has been assumed so far: there is a set of ‘non-ideal burdens’, actions that are costly in the short term but necessary to make an effective international response to climate change politically feasible, and it is these that must be distributed fairly. Such a distribution, Maltais (2014) argues, requires economically powerful states to show ‘climate leadership’ by taking unilateral actions, because they are well connected to the problem and have the capacity to effectuate structural change.7 Maltais is right in problematizing the non- ideal problem: the default framing certainly seems like a misrepresentation of a situation in which almost no one complies. But it should be noted that one thereby leaves the partial compliance interpretation of non-ideal theory. Maltais’s (2014) discussion of the normative ground of climate leadership is of a different kind. It is more akin to the second interpretation of non-ideal theory, to which I will now turn. IV. Realistic Climate Justice An ironic twist of the partial compliance interpretation is that its suggested treatment of noncompliance risks furthering even more noncompliance. If compliers are required to shoulder residual burdens of non-compliers, their motivation is tested, and, if stretched to its limit, the result could be yet more noncompliance, not only with the additional, residual burden, but also with respect to the initial, ideal burden. Of course, this need not happen, but one can think of cases more generally where it seems likely, such as when one of two younger siblings defaults on a joint enterprise and leaves the other to singlehandedly bear the full burden. It is anyhow surprising that non-ideal theory thus understood may be more demanding than ideal theory. Why would making the demands of justice more stringent make it more likely that they are met in the future, one is inclined to ask. Whether or not this has been the reason, some climate ethicists have used non-ideal climate justice in a radically different sense. The proposals considered in this section all, in different ways, challenge the standard modus operandi of climate ethics and call for a rapprochement to climate policy. Even if not all of these proposals are meant to replace existing ideal theories – they, at least, question standard methodological choices and defend alternative ways of doing climate ethics. The common core is realism: start with an accurate description of people, politics and policies and then evaluate and make normative proposals. The difficulty, of course, is doing that without too much of a concession to realpolitik. That is, to avoid reducing normative principles to political strategy, and being apologetic of the status quo. 7 Alexandre Gajevic Sayegh (2016) points out a first, less radical, way in which principles of climate justice should be realistic: they need to take into account the relevant empirical circumstances. Climate ethicists cannot – and do not – settle for only very abstract formulations of general principles of justice, such as the principle of equality. They take into account things like the currency of equality. An inattentive assumption of GHG emissions as the distribuendum to be equalised leads to implausible results, as some individuals reasonably need to emit more than others.8 Such facts should be taken into account, and so should of course the facts from climate science, and facts about how GHG emissions are measured, what incentive effects policies are likely to give rise to, etc. Only then can one hope to formulate principles of climate justice that are action guiding, as Gajevic Sayegh (2016) rightly points out. Indeed, otherwise one would not have formulated principles of climate justice at all. Nor should Roser’s (2016) proposal to ground climate protection in already existing motivation be controversial. His idea is ‘to choose the least unjust option within the bounds of motivation, however insufficient motivation may currently be’ (Roser 2016, p. 84). He further assumes that there are actions that provide better climate protection, yet are compatible with the limited motivation of present agents (he calls these ‘the motivation-compatible set of options’). These are actions (and policies) that are sometimes referred to as ‘no-regret options’ and ‘win-win options’ due to having co-benefits other than climate protection (e.g. cleaner air and fewer respiratory diseases) or directly saving costs (e.g. energy efficiency), but also ideas inspired by studies in psychology and behavioural economics, such as deferring the costs of climate action, ‘green nudges’, debiasing techniques, as well as a proposal to simplify the measurement of climate injustice: instead of a comprehensive evaluation one could focus only on the effects on world poverty and thus create a kind of ‘poverty index’ for climate action.9 Most of these proposals seem promising, which is hardly surprising given that they are designed to be just that.10 It is also easy to agree with Roser that: ‘Searching for, engaging in, and promoting such strategies is one of the weighty moral imperatives in an unjust world such as ours’ (2016, p. 93). Climate ethicists should continue to engage in the kind of interdisciplinary work cognisant of the relevant political facts with moral reflection that Roser (2016) has set the example for. Maltais (2016) and Light and Taraska (2016) advance two similar approaches. Maltais (2016) argues that climate ethicists should focus less on ‘fine-tuning general distributive principles’, and more on the normative dimension of reforms proposed to overcome the political inertia (e.g. reforming the multilateralism of UNFCCC). By evaluating these, one could advance ‘mediating strategies’, which, in a piecemeal manner, make the political situation more tractable. Similarly, Light and Taraska (2016) exemplifies policy-relevant climate ethics. They provide a rather detailed outline of the current pledge-and-review system of the Paris Agreement, and also characterise some of the domestic political obstacles to more ambitious commitments. On that basis, they propose a ‘workable option with significant potential’ (2016, p. 180): to phase out ‘short-lived climate pollutants’. As with some of Roser’s proposals, it is hard to disagree. But what should be more controversial is the new role for the climate ethicist implicitly assumed. It seems to be that of steering politicians out of the current impasse by making concrete and here and now politically feasible recommendations. This role, which is similar to the policy analyst, is no doubt important, though not clearly one that climate ethicists should exclusively adopt. A consideration against is that it gives up on the central discussion of background injustice, that is, scrutinising how a number of individually fair and freely entered policies and agreements could 8 produce an injustice on the aggregate level; a ‘compound injustice’, in the words of Shue (2014, pp. 36-41). Another criticism is that such a bottom-up approach is too narrowly focused, and because of that fails to address spillover effects between different domains of concern. Even so, I do believe that climate ethicists should consider adopting it on the condition that they, like Light and Taraska, have insight into the policy process. But, then, be aware that it does not make the work of traditional normative theory obsolete. Martin Kowarsch and Ottmar Edenhofer’s (2016) ‘pathway exploration approach’ is to some extent similar to the ones just considered: climate ethicists should evaluate policy pathways, much like the policy analyst. But their more specific proposal, that the ethical discussion should be integrated in the assessments of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC), suggests a different take on policy-relevant work. It must be squared with the mission statement of the IPCC, which among other things states that ‘[t]he work of the organization is therefore policy-relevant and yet policy-neutral, never policy-prescriptive’. If Kowarsch and Edenhofer’s proposal is simply to strengthen the evaluative assessments that are already a part of the IPCC11, then that is fine, but perhaps somewhat futile. But if it is to give the IPCC a more straightforward normative project, it is not compatible with the mission statement and likely to meet fierce resistance.12 Either way, if the ambition is to make climate ethics more practically relevant, it is more promising to follow Maltais, Light and Taraska in integrating it with relevant political practices, rather than with the scientific community. There is, however, one feature of Kowarsch and Edenhofer’s approach that I want to note: that the distinction between implementation and justification is blurred. They stress that ideal principles should be revised, if they cannot be implemented in any acceptable way. This may be an interesting contrast to some ideas discussed in the previous section.13 Darrel Moellendorf (2016) also presents a policy-relevant approach to climate ethics. Because climate change is such an urgent issue, he argues, we cannot wait for a fully specified ideal theory, nor fall back on non-ideal theory (as that presupposes ideal theory).14 The only normative guidance possible thus is that of the norms nation states already are committed to in virtue of having ratified UNFCCC: The goods and burdens of climate change abatement should be distributed according to these norms. The obvious problem with such a proposal however is that by being a result of international diplomacy, the norms of UNFCCC are abstract and rather non- committal. Take what is among the clearest norms prescribed in it (also Moellendorf’s example): ‘the right to sustainable development’ (1992, Art. 3.4/4.7). This has been understood as recognising the claim of ‘Non-Annex I Parties’ (among them China, India, Brazil) to develop and grow their economies, even if that amounts to additional GHG emissions.15 But what actions are prescribed by that recognition is unclear, and so is the application of the concept of needs (more on this below). Moellendorf devotes considerable space to justifying that the norms should be taken seriously, but should rather have worried about explicating and specifying them. V. Transitional Climate Justice Consider again the reluctance of nation states, local governments, business and other relevant actors to take appropriate climate measures. The situation may be one in which ‘there is no allocation of GHG emissions […] that is both morally tolerable and, at present, politically feasible as long as most economies are dependent for energy upon carbon-based fuels, that is, fossil 9 fuels’ (Shue 2014, p. 225). If fairly dealing with climate change clashes with entrenched interests in the fossil fuel economy, there may be no practicable alternative but to aim for a technological solution, to make renewables, like wind and solar, competitive.16 The transition to a clean- energy economy, however, also raises questions of justice. Shue (2014) makes a case for transitional climate justice. He notes that in the deadlocked political situation one must engage in incremental improvements on the status quo. This raises the question about what compromises are morally acceptable. A question that cannot be answered merely by pointing to ‘ultimate goals’: there is a need for ‘guidelines for transitions’ (Shue 2014, p. 58). Although such guidelines probably share some features of the principles for dealing with injustice (considered in section III), they nevertheless are of a different type. The ‘transition’ is not, or at least not directly, to the ultimate goals of ideal theory.17 Rather, it is to a clean-energy economy. The theoretical focus is on giving ground to and justification for grievances such a transition may bring about. In this connection, Shue (2014, pp. 133-141) distinguishes between different ranges normative standards may take. With respect to some ideals a relatively long transition period is allowed before it ought to be fully complied with, with respect to others a much shorter one. Then, there are ‘minimum standards’, which ‘must be satisfied as quickly as is humanly possible’ (Shue 2014, p. 134). In numerous chapters, Shue (2014) argues for two minimum standards to form the transitional principles of climate justice. To govern the intergenerational dimension, he proposes a ‘do no harm’ principle, which prescribes precautionary actions to prevent harm from climate change being inflicted on future generations, irrespective of the relative probability of the harm above a certain minimum likelihood threshold (Shue 2014, chs. 8, 11, 12, 14, 16). And for the international distribution, a basic needs principle (Shue 2014, chs. 2, 6, 9, 17). These minimum standards could be described as sufficientarian. They set thresholds under which no one should fall: no one should suffer damage as a result of climate change and no one’s basic needs should be left unmet as a result of actions to mitigate climate change. Shue defends their correctness as guidelines for transitions without invoking a complete theory of justice.18 But problems arise as one tries to specify what concrete climate policies they recommend. To apply Shue’s ‘do no harm’ principle it seems the current generation would need to just stop any GHG-generating activities: already the current stock of GHG is dangerous (cf. Shue 2014, p. 309, fn. 32). But why should we not take into account probabilities (even if they are hard to get at) and make comparisons to other policy objectives? It is at any rate not a minimum standard to recommend the prevention of any risk of harm. On the contrary, it is a very demanding one. The other principle is less controversial, but still problematic. In the international policy community, there is, at least in the abstract, consensus about something like the needs principle, expressed in the UNFCCC (1992, Art. 3.1). But the contentious issues arise in the specifications required to make the principle actionable. There are, for instance, different ways of satisfying basic needs: some based on fossil fuels, others on renewables. In order to evaluate such policy topics as climate finance, technology transfer and capacity-building, the basic needs principle must be more concretely specified. Then, more generally, the transition to a clean-energy economy raises normative questions about what means may be taken to that end (see Roser and Seidel 2017, chs. 18-20) that cannot be resolved merely by the needs principle. The challenge is to formulate transitional principles that are not too abstract and thus leave too much to the political process. 10 VI. Conclusion Having sorted out three different senses of non-ideal climate justice, it is natural to ask whether one or the other is more fruitful for future theorising.19 But to answer that I believe one needs a description of the political practices they are meant to regulate that is more detailed than what can be provided here (but see e.g. Keohane and Victor 2016). I can only note that as the Paris Agreement has entered into force, the structure of the main climate regime is now in place. As already noted, the overall ambition for the world at large and an approximate timetable for reaching it has been agreed on. Also other features of this institutional framework are likely to circumscribe the role and function of normative theories, although institutional reform and innovation of course are possible and probably necessary. The following normative question remains anyway: how to fairly distribute the burdens of a transition away from fossil fuels to sources of clean energy? The reviewed literature highlights some concerns important to consider in answering that. The discussion of noncompliance may seem hopelessly out of touch with the unfortunate state of climate politics, but still is a reminder that the action space is subject to change. What is politically infeasible today may be a central part of a political consensus tomorrow. That this is so raises questions about how such transitions come about. One suggestion is that it is by gradually realising an independently justified ideal theory. But as has been suggested above, such a view seems unrealistic, and furthermore could neglect normative complaints specific to the circumstances of this particular transition. It is more promising to take into account various feasibility constraints – psychological, institutional, and perhaps also those given by particular moral judgments – in formulating ideal principles. Elaborating on the reviewed literature, this can be done by formulating ideal principles specific to a particular context (e.g. the current climate regime) or conception of the agent in question (e.g. negotiating nation states), rather than assuming a more general scope. The challenge is to connect to the motivation of relevant actors so that normative principles guide their actions, without thereby uncritically accepting the status quo. Possibly, this can be addressed by providing a relatively thick description of what matters to the agents facing the distributive problem, the ones who must strike a fair deal. On common conceptions of fairness, such as ‘the original position’ (Rawls 1999), there is nothing that prevents a richer description of the person than what is standardly supplied in the literature on climate justice. Other factors than contribution, basic needs and ability to pay – such as co-benefits, competitiveness, and reputation – may partly determine what is a fair distribution of costs, even if they do not weigh equally. A final lesson from the above is that climate ethics better work towards the more concrete and particular. This could involve engaging in the kind of policy-relevant work that several of the theorists considered above suggest, but it could also extend to evaluating yet more concrete proposals, such as that of a feed-in tariff or an aviation tax. Beyond that, one can only conclude that the role of the climate ethicist in a just climate transition is still not clearly and convincingly articulated. 11 Note on contributor Eric Brandstedt is a Post-Doctoral Research Fellow at the Centre for Philosophy of Natural and Social Science (CPNSS), London School of Economics, working on a project about the relation between climate ethics and climate politics. His research interests are climate justice, the methodology of normative theorising, and intergenerational justice. He has recently been published in Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Moral Philosophy and Politics and Environmental Politics. Acknowledgments I am grateful to Fergus Green, Ylwa Sjölin Wirling, Joshua Wells, Susanne Burri, and Laura Valentini for comments, suggestions and general discussion of draft versions of this article. This work was generously supported by the Swedish Research Council under grant number 437- 2014-6692. Notes 1 This is also the received interpretation of John Rawls’s (1999, p. 216) original presentation of the distinction (see e.g. Simmons 2010). 2 For references see Hohl and Roser (2011, p. 478). The claim is implausible absent some moral justification for why the noncompliance of some should dissolve compliers’ obligations. Perhaps this could be provided (see Miller 2011), but as it stands it just collapses normative theory to a description of what agents are actually doing. 3 ‘Burden’ here is understood in an encompassing way, including not only emission reductions, but also measures to adapt to climate change, as well as actions to promote and facilitate future solutions. 4 Caney’s (2016a, p. 16) own ideal theory is a cosmopolitan egalitarianism, based on the capabilities framework. What matters fundamentally thus is that all present and future people have equal capabilities to lead a good life. The ultimate aim of any climate transition thus is to approximate such a fair distribution of life opportunities. 5 See the overview provided by Roser and Seidel (2017). The most notable deviations are some defending a ‘beneficiary pays principle’ and some defending so-called ‘grandfathering’. 6 See also Hohl and Roser (2011, pp. 495-497). 12 7 Shue (2014, ch. 15) similarly argues for climate leadership: In order to avoid paralysis, nation states are required to unilaterally do their fair share in mitigating climate change, even without promise that others will follow. 8 See Caney’s (2012) compelling critique. Perhaps partly as a result of such criticism, the assumption is less commonplace in climate ethics today than it used to be. 9 See also Light and Taraska (2016), who also discuss co-benefits of climate action, and Pickering (2016), who discusses strategic communication. 10 But see Shue 2014, p. 210, for some possible objections. 11 Several climate ethicists, such as John Broome, Lukas Meyer and Simon Caney, contributed to the latest IPCC (2014) report, in particular to WGIII, ch. 3 (‘Social, Economic, and Ethical Concepts and Methods’). 12 An example of that is Christian Seidel’s (2016) proposal of a ‘government house climate ethics’, situated in the IPCC. The idea is in effect for the IPCC to act as a philosopher king, issuing normative recommendations to the political process. But this seems unpromising: not only would it likely be procedurally unfair, but also counterproductive. 13 Whether or not it does so depends on how ethically acceptable application is understood. Traditional ideal theorists are also worried about that, as I described in section III. The difference, if any, is that whereas they have a fixed idea about what is ethically acceptable (namely, what their ideal theories prescribe), the alternative is to allow more particular judgments to play a justificatory role. To clarify: Kowarsch and Edenhofer (2016) do not make this point, but it is one way of making sense of their criticism against climate ethics. 14 His main argument against ideal theory is that it is impractical to fully specify such a theory (2016, pp. 107-110). But he does not say anything about what is wrong with those already specified ideal theories, such as the one from Caney considered above. In what sense, if any, are they impractical? 15 Note that since the UNFCCC was first drafted and signed in 1992, some of these countries have had strong economic development, with the result of higher standards of living but also higher GHG emission levels. In 2006, China surpassed the US as the world biggest absolute emitter of GHGs, yet it is still a Non-Annex I Party. 16 Note that also a technological solution, which likely involves quite some political steering, is bound to meet resistance from vested interests in the fossil fuel economy. The claim is just that it is more feasible than the alternative of just stop using fossil fuels. 17 My rendition of transitional theory thus differs from Valentini’s (2012), according to which it concerns what gradual steps of justice-improvement can be taken, possibly without consulting an end-state theory. 13 18 Amartya Sen (2009) presents a more explicit argument for why ideal theory (what he calls ‘the transcendental approach’) is neither necessary nor sufficient for such comparative judgments. 19 Note a more general conclusion suggested by the discussion above: the distinction is rather blurry. If there are different kinds of non-ideal theory, they are likely rather similar in structure and extension. 14 References Barry, B., 2003. Sustainability and intergenerational justice. In: A. Light and H. Rolston III, eds. Environmental ethics. An anthology. Malden, MA: Blackwell, 487-499. Caney, S., 2005. Cosmopolitan justice, responsibility, and global climate change. Leiden journal of international law, 18 (4), 747-775. Caney, S., 2012. Just emissions. Philosophy & public affairs, 40 (4), 255-300. Caney, S., 2016a. The struggle for climate justice in a nonideal world. Midwest studies in philosophy, 40 (1), 9–26. Caney, S., 2016b. Climate change and non-ideal theory: six ways of responding to non- compliance. In: C. Heyward and D. Roser, eds. Climate justice in a non-ideal world. Oxford: Oxford university press, 21–42. Gajevic Sayegh, A., 2016. Justice in a non-ideal world: the case of climate change. Critical review of international social and political philosophy. Heyward, C. and Roser, D., eds., 2016. Climate justice in a non-ideal world. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hohl, S. and Roser D., 2011. Stepping in for the polluters? Climate justice under partial compliance. Analyse & kritik, 33 (2), 477–500. Intergovernmental panel on climate change (IPCC). 2014. Fifth assessment report: working group III (Mitigation of climate change). Cambridge: Cambridge university press. Keohane, R. O. and Victor, D. G., 2016. Cooperation and discord in global climate policy. Nature climate change, 6, 570-575. Kowarsch, M. and Edenhofer, O., 2016. Principles of pathways? Improving the contribution of philosophical ethics to climate policy. In: C. Heyward and D. Roser, eds. Climate justice in a non-ideal world. Oxford: Oxford university press, 296–317. Light, A. and Taraska G., 2016. A responsible path: enhancing action on short-lived climate pollutants. In: C. Heyward and D. Roser, eds. Climate justice in a non-ideal world. Oxford: Oxford university press, 169–188. Maltais, A., 2013. Radically non-ideal climate politics and the obligation to at least vote green. Environmental values, 22 (5), 589–608. Maltais, A., 2014. Failing international climate politics and the fairness of going first. Political studies, 62 (3), 618-633. Maltais, A., 2016. A climate of disorder: what to do about the obstacles to effective climate politics. In: C. Heyward and D. Roser, eds. Climate justice in a non-ideal world. Oxford: Oxford university press, 43–63. 15 Moellendorf, D., 2016. Taking UNFCCC norms seriously. In: C. Heyward and D. Roser, eds. Climate justice in a non-ideal world. Oxford: Oxford university press, 104–121. Miller, D., 2011. Taking up the slack? Responsibility and justice in situations of partial compliance. In: C. Knight and Z. Stemplowska, eds. Responsibility and distributive justice. Oxford: Oxford university press, 230-245. Pickering, J., 2016. Moral language in climate politics. In: C. Heyward and D. Roser, eds. Climate justice in a non-ideal world. Oxford: Oxford university press, 255–276. Rawls, J., 1999. A theory of justice, rev edn. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, [1971] 1999. Roser, D., 2016. Reducing injustice within the bounds of motivation. In: C. Heyward and D. Roser, eds. Climate justice in a non-ideal world. Oxford: Oxford university press, 83–103. Roser, D. and Seidel, C., 2017. Climate justice: an introduction. Abingdon, Oxon: Routledge. Seidel, C. 2016. The cost of moralizing: how about a ‘government house climate ethics’? In: C. Heyward and D. Roser, eds. Climate justice in a non-ideal world. Oxford: Oxford university press, 277–295. Sen, A. 2009. The idea of justice. London: Allen lane/Penguin books. Shue, H., 2014. Climate justice: vulnerability and protection. Oxford: Oxford university Press. Simmons, J., 2010. Ideal and nonideal theory. Philosophy & public affairs, 38 (1), 5-36. UNFCCC, 1992. United Nations framework convention on climate change. http://unfccc.int/key_documents/the_convention/items/2853.php UNFCCC, 2015. Adoption of the Paris Agreement. Report No. FCCC/CP/2015/L.9/Rev.1, http://unfccc.int/resource/docs/2015/cop21/eng/l09r01.pdf Valentini, L., 2012. Ideal vs. non-ideal theory: a conceptual map. Philosophy compass 7 (9), 654– 664. http://unfccc.int/key_documents/the_convention/items/2853.php http://unfccc.int/resource/docs/2015/cop21/eng/l09r01.pdf New Journal Cover(accepted version refereed) Brandstedt_Non-Ideal Climate Justice_Author_2017 work_3pkikopr4jdxtkqsv6iejlwqa4 ---- josi_010.tex Journal of Social Issues, Vol. 62, No. 2, 2006, pp. 393--409 Doing Justice Intelligently in Civil Society John Braithwaite∗ Regulatory Institutions Network, Research School of Social Sciences, Australian National University Empirically, justice might be immanently holistic—with procedural, distributive, restorative, and social justice positively correlated. Restorative justice may be about creating spaces where the various imperfectly correlated facets of holistic justice might cohere. State institutions of justice (such as criminal courts) with deeply embedded traditions of narrowing the meaning of justice (to proportional punishment, for example) are less fertile soil for holistic justice than civil society. Beyond a move to holism and to civil society, the contributions to this special issue imply a move to what Sherman calls “emotionally intelligent justice.” This means nurturing the expression of vulnerable emotions and trying to avert the provocation of aggressive or stigmatizing emotions. Restorative Justice and Criminal Justice An impressive feature of this special issue is the way it draws upon data from societies as diverse as the United States, Australia, New Zealand, South Africa, and Bangladesh. This reflects the fact that restorative justice is now a global social movement for the transformation of legal justice. Its heartland is criminal law where 2000 saw all nations at the UN Congress on the Prevention of Crime and Treatment of Offenders vote to encourage the development of restorative justice programs. But restorative justice is proving an increasingly influential idea in programs for the care and protection of abused or neglected children, school bullying, business regulation, and international peacekeeping and peacemaking, among other domains (Roche, this issue). As Maxwell and Morris (this issue) explain, New Zealand research and development on the idea of family group conferences to respond to youth offenders was particularly important in the history ∗Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to John Braithwaite, Regulatory Institutions Network, Research School of Social Sciences, Australian National University, ACT-0200, Australia [e-mail: John.Braithwaite@anu.edu.au]. 393 C© 2006 The Society for the Psychological Study of Social Issues 394 Braithwaite of restorative justice. Yet perhaps even more influential, in terms of how widely it has been copied in the northern hemisphere, has been New Zealand’s development of the conferencing idea for application to care and protection conferences with the families of abused or neglected children. In academic writing and social movement politics, as in the mass media, criminal justice always grabs more headlines than other forms of social regulation. A more principled reason, however, for the prominence given to criminal jus- tice in this special issue is that it is the criminal side of restorative justice innovation that has also attracted most research efforts, including some randomized controlled trials that have found substantial effects of restorative justice in reducing subse- quent reoffending, though only for some kinds of offenders (Sherman, 2003), and in reducing the suffering of victims of crime (Strang et al., this issue). In 2001, the Canadian Department of Justice was able to conduct a meta-analysis of no fewer than 32 evaluations of restorative justice with credible controls (Latimer, Dowden, & Muise, 2001). It found a modest though significant association of restorative justice with lower reoffending, higher perceptions of fairness by victims and of- fenders, and superior implementation of agreements/orders in restorative justice compared to control cases. A recent updated and refined Canadian government meta-analysis by Bonta, Jesseman, Rugge, and Cormier (2006) replicated this re- sult on reoffending, while reporting that the effect size was significantly greater for studies published from 1996. While almost all developed nations and many developing ones have restora- tive justice programs for youth offending today, they mostly remain marginal programs, very much in the shadow of the punitive paradigm that continues to dominate youth justice. This is a second reason why New Zealand has special significance. It is the only nation where restorative justice is the mainstream, pre- sumptive path for youth offending. As the Maxwell and Morris article shows, unless the offence is murder or manslaughter, youth offences always go either to a restorative police caution, a restorative diversion, a family group conference, or to court followed by a conference. They simply never go the court-punishment route bypassing any restorative process. While many other countries, such as Austria and Norway, have massive restorative justice programs, New Zealand remains dis- tinctive because restorative justice consistently trumps punitive courtroom justice as the presumptive path for youth. The impact has been substantial, cutting youth custodial sentences to around a third of what they had been prior to the restorative justice reform. As Maxwell and Morris point out, New Zealand is also interesting for the bicultural way its restorative justice programs have developed—influenced by Maori custom and law, eschewing other parts of that tradition, and incorporating notions such as victim rights from Western legal traditions. Restorative justice is not a nostalgic longing for a lost past, but practical experimentation into the future with learnings from both the past and the present. Doing Justice Intelligently in Civil Society 395 The New Zealand innovation of moving beyond one-on-one victim–offender mediation to a conference where family members and other supporters of both the offender and of the victim attend, as well as representatives of the state and/or the community, was a step with many implications. It makes the imbalance of power dynamics quite different, more muddied. Instead of a mediation between say a domineering male adult and a dominated female child, we have a conference for the same incident in which there may be adults and children, men and women, more and less domineering and articulate people on both sides. The Maxwell and Morris (1993) program of empirical research has been among the most important contributions on this question, showing that adult womens’ voices, particularly mothers’ voices, are greatly empowered by the conference process, though chil- dren’s voices are still rather more muted than advocates would like to see. Aral, Burris, and Shearing (2002) found in their analysis of 942 South African peace- making gatherings on the Zwelethemba model that is discussed by Roche (this issue) that 60% of the participants and 65% of the facilitators were women. The shame dynamics discussed in the latter part of this special issue are dif- ferent in a conference than in a dyadic mediation. Criminal offenders are often criminal offenders because they are good at shielding themselves from the conse- quences of the harm they have inflicted on others. Meeting the victim can make this harder. But still the shield that protects them from confronting the conse- quences of what they have done can continue to work as they sullenly stare at the ground while the victim recounts her suffering. We sometimes observe, how- ever, that if an offender’s mother begins to sob as she listens to the suffering of the victim, the offender will be more vulnerable to his mother’s pain and to her compassion and humanity. So the New Zealand innovation of the conference in my view brought more complex emotional dynamics that were more productive in engendering empathy. This connected to Maori ways of thinking about justice, which saw it as barbaric to allow an offender to stand alone accused of a crime. The offender should be surrounded by the support of his loved ones in the face of terrible allegations against him and they should stand ready to share the burden of the responsibility that falls to him. From the shame management perspective that we see in the articles by Harris, Ahmed/Braithwaite, and Morrison (this issue), the shame of letting one’s family down is easier to transcend. We can put it behind us in a ritual that emphatically demonstrates the forgiveness and support of our family. A conference places less of a burden on the facilitator than a dyadic medi- ation places on the mediator. When dominating or abusive speech breaks out in a conference, hopefully there will be someone else in the circle who will speak to curb the dominating speech. If the offender says something to a victim that leaves him bereft of hope, there will mostly be someone else in the circle who will offer the victim comfort and support. When in a dyadic mediation only the medi- ator is available to comfort the cruelly treated or to put down dominating speech, 396 Braithwaite the mediator risks being seen as on the side of the party on whose behalf she must intervene. More importantly, when the mediator is forced to intervene in this way, the empowerment philosophy of restorative justice—that power rests with the stakeholders rather than the professional—is put at risk. Dyadic mediations are therefore also more vulnerable to the incompetent mediator. In contrast, empow- ered conference participants often speak up to compensate for the incompetence of the worst facilitators. The conference ideology is to empower citizens as opposed to professionals. Neither incompetent citizens nor an incompetent facilitator need be fatal. So we do see, in our observational research, conferences that are con- ducted with massive incompetence on the part of the facilitator, combined with some equally clumsy interventions by some stakeholders, but conferences that are nevertheless successful because of competent interventions by other empowered citizen stakeholders. Finally, the existence of a wider plurality of voices in the conference circle than in a dyadic mediation means that there are better prospects for creative problem- solving ideas to emerge. There are also more people who can offer ideas and practical help for plural forms of support to ensure that agreements are honored. So if it is decided that an anger management program would be a good idea, but then someone points out that a court once before ordered anger management and the offender rarely turned up, a relative might offer to pick her up every Tuesday evening to take responsibility for ensuring that this time she attends regularly. Plurality of perspectives enriches the problem-solving part of the conference. This is not to say that there might not be certain ideas that could only be broached by an adjournment in which the two principal players in the idea talk about it one-on- one. Backstage, during coffee breaks, “private family time,” farewells in the car park after the conference, we observe all manner of dyadic and triadic healing to be given space to occur. A research agenda for the future of restorative justice is about how to enable moving back and forth between wider and narrower groups of stakeholders to maximize restoration of victims, offenders, and communities of relationships. An irony in the aftermath of the mainstreamed paradigm change of New Zealand conferencing is that today we probably see more innovation with radi- cally new modalities of restorative circles in North America, especially Canada, than in the Antipodes. In the United States where restorative justice is utterly at the margins of an overwhelmingly punitive system, there is no mainstream orthodoxy of restorative justice. Consequently, in the many hundreds (Bazemore & Schiff, 2005) of little community programs that are eked out of the punitive mainstream, creativity reigns. An example is the North Minneapolis African American Cir- cles. Here a series of circles are held for each offender. The first is an interview circle where the program is described in detail so the young offender can make a decision on whether to participate in the program. The crime itself is not dis- cussed in this circle. In one of them observed by Declan Roche, it was discovered Doing Justice Intelligently in Civil Society 397 that the young person was interested in basketball, so some men in the circle went to watch him play during the next week. The second circle discusses the harm caused by the crime and what might need to be done to put things right. Meanwhile a separate circle is being held to support the victim. The two circles can then decide to come together for a more conventional healing circle in which victims, offenders, and their supporters meet. After a plan of action is agreed in that circle, a follow-up circle is scheduled for some months into the future to mon- itor implementation. Finally, a celebration circle is held when the agreement is completed. This elaborate set of circles is of course very time consuming and is only affordable because almost all the work is put in by community volunteers. My point is that it is innovative, indeed pathbreaking, but that the innovation is incubated on the fringe of a U.S. justice system that leaves citizens in high crime communities such as North Minneapolis so dissatisfied with the way the sys- tem grinds down both offenders and victims that they become grass-roots justice innovators. Justice That Is Restorative A number of the contributions to this issue—in particular those of Roche, Pennell, Ahmed/Braithwaite, and Morrison—are about restorative justice for mostly non-criminal matters. Yet restorative justice has a core focus that is more specific than problem solving or conflict resolution of any kind. Its ultimate con- cern is some kind of injustice that must be dealt with. It might be confronted by conflict resolution, but equally by conflict prevention or problem solving, so long as what is at issue is injustice prevention or resolution of injustice. An in- justice does not need to be a criminal harm, it can be a tort or some other kind of civil wrong, it can be the injustice of a school bully who teases other children (Ahmed/Braithwaite, Morrison, this issue), of families who neglect their children (Pennell, this issue), of corporations who treat their workers unfairly, armies fight- ing a war, or local communities that fail to provide basic security for citizens (Roche, this issue). The justice idea has also become theoretically central for restorativists. This is why Tom Tyler’s (1990) work is so pivotal. Because restorativists talk justice, they should walk the talk—be just in the way they transact restorative justice. The implication of Tyler’s (this issue) work is that we are not likely to restore if we are not procedurally fair in the process of restoration. Barnes (1999) and Strang’s (2002) work based on random assignment of criminal cases (to court versus restorative justice conferences) suggests that restorative processes mostly are perceived by offenders and victims as more procedurally fair than courtroom justice. It may be that restorative justice is perceived as more procedurally fair because stakeholders are given a direct voice rather than having to channel their communication through the mouthpiece of a lawyer. Yet there seems more to it 398 Braithwaite than that. The Sherman et al. (1998), Barnes (1999), and Strang (2002) randomized control trial data also suggest that victims and offenders are more likely to perceive their rights as respected, that they are not discriminated against on the basis of the race, sex, age, etc., and various other facets of procedural justice beyond voice, when justice is transacted restoratively. It may be that justice is immanently holistic. This idea comes through in Bishop Tutu’s interpretation of the meaning of the Xhosa concept of ubuntu (see Roche, this issue). Ubuntu seems to incorporate not only restorative and procedural justice, but distributive justice (people with ubuntu “share what they have”) and relational justice (“We belong in a bundle of life”). I want to read Tutu (1999) as reading ubuntu as holistic justice. Rather than regarding legal justice and social justice as quite separate things with separate institutions being best equipped to deliver them (say the criminal justice system for legal justice, the welfare system for social justice) we regard legal and social justice as facets of justice conceived more holistically. It follows that we might want to craft institutions that pro- mote holistic justice making, as opposed to specializing in one kind of justice or another. While justice may be to some extent immanently holistic, it cannot be totally holistic; otherwise there would be no point in distinguishing procedural justice from the justice of outcomes. Procedural justice has been conceived in the literature as having a number of facets—including consistency, correctability, decision accu- racy, impartiality, ethicality, and process control (Lind & Tyler, 1988; Leventhal, 1980)—but these facets tend to be moderately highly intercorrelated. Second, we find that procedural and distributive justice tend to be positively correlated (Wenzel (2000, 2002) reporting correlations of 0.2–0.4). Hence, one of the arguments of restorative justice theorists has been that restorative justice, compared to existing justice practices, contributes to procedural justice, perceived fairness of outcomes (distributive justice) and indeed social justice (Braithwaite, 2002: pp. 54–130). Zehr (1995) argues that this holism in the conception of justice is to be found in the biblical notion of justice as shalom. The intuition about the immanent holism of the shalom way of thinking about justice is that a restorative justice process that seeks to empower stakeholders to repair the harm of an injustice will produce outcomes that are more distributively satisfying to stakeholders than a process that seeks to deliver equal punishments to equal wrongs. If we put the problem in the center of the circle, as opposed to putting the person in the center, we are more likely to come up with a solution to the problem that is perceived by the participants to deliver just distributive benefits. In contrast, if we put the person in the center of the circle and ask what is the right punishment according to some narrowly puni- tive theory of justice, it will turn out that the right punishment according to this theory will almost always be the wrong solution to the problem. Punitive justice can be integrated into holistic justice. Sometimes it is vital to protect community safety and to deliver distributive benefits to potential victims of injustice through Doing Justice Intelligently in Civil Society 399 deterrence. But punitive justice is not the main game of holistic justice. When lawyers make it the main game by insisting on consistent application of the prin- ciple of equal punishment for equal wrongs, holistic justice is placed beyond our reach. Heather Strang’s (2002) writing suggests that a narrower just deserts objective allows less leeway for a wider contract zone in which a win–win outcome can be crafted where both victims and offenders can be better off than they would have been without the encounter with the justice system. Strang’s (2002) evidence that win–win outcomes are more likely in restorative justice conferences, while win– lose and lose–lose victim–offender outcomes are more likely in courtroom justice, means restorative justice produces outcomes that are more generally conceived as distributively fair. Strang et al. (this issue) show that the way victims can improve their cir- cumstances through restorative justice are various. In their randomized controlled trials, victims in restorative justice processes are more than twice as likely to be afraid, to be angry, and less than half as likely to be sympathetic to offenders before compared to after restorative justice conferences. Referring also to Angel’s (2005) results on the impact of restorative justice in reducing post-traumatic stress, Strang et al. come up with the innovative theoretical interpretation that when restorative justice is a successful interaction ritual (Collins, 2004), it may give victims the emotional energy to gain cognitive mastery of their emotions, supplanting condi- tioned fear with empathy for an offender in dire life circumstances. Hence, another dimension of the potential holism of restorative justice is that the justice it theo- rizes in the Strang et al. contribution, is not simply justice for offenders, but for all stakeholders affected by the injustice, including its direct victims. Law that is seen as legitimate, and therefore as enabling self-regulation, also underwrites a more holistic justice than law that is seen as illegitimate and that must be externally coerced (Tyler, this issue). Such coerced, illegitimate law is a law of the authorities, rather than the law of a whole people, a living law of a civil society. We have seen that greater control of process in the hands of stakeholders, as opposed to justice professionals, might also explain why restorative justice is perceived as more procedurally fair. We can also intuit why justice may be imma- nently holistic by going in the opposite direction in ways suggested by the writings of Rawls (1971) and indeed most other writers on justice. An unjust procedure will be more open to domination by the person with the most power rather than the person with the best case and so will lead both to less fair outcomes and to social injustice by virtue of domination by the powerful. Relevant to this prospect of holistic justice through restorative institutions is the earlier claim about how restorative justice creates more cross-cutting and counterbalanced power imbal- ances than an encounter between a domineering male and a dominated woman, an adult and a child, a school bully and a nerd, a sophisticated corporate criminal and 400 Braithwaite an unsophisticated consumer, a fast-talking lawyer, and a slow-talking mentally disabled victim of crime. The fact that justice is not fully holistic—that procedural and distributive justice often conflict, for example—means that there is value and great intellectual interest in studying the tensions between different versions of justice. Tom Tyler’s (Tyler, 1990; Tyler & Blader, 2000; Tyler & Dawes, 1993; Tyler & Huo, 2001) work on why the justice of procedures matters more than the distributive justice of outcomes is a pre-eminent example. Restorative justice innovation takes a different tack, however. It says that because there appears to be an immanent holism of justice as ubuntu or shalom, why not search for institutional ideas that maximize the synergy of holistic justice? Then it theorizes restorative justice as that institutional idea. For example, there is the theory of the structure of a restorative justice conference in comparison to that of a court case. We invite to a court case those who can, through their testimony, inflict maximum damage to the other side. We invite to the conference those who can offer maximum support to their own side, be it the victim or the offender side. Such plurality forces us to see civil society rather than the state as the most important sites where justice making is done. This is one interpretation of why Declan Roche (2003, see also Roche, this issue) was able to demonstrate superior capabilities for some forms of restorative justice to hold police accountable to citizens affected by excessive use of force and unfair victimization, compared to courtrooms. Braithwaite (2002: pp. 17–24) has shown how Australian corporate crime enforcement that is restorative and responsive can foster a public discussion that transforms the regulation of an industry or create a tax system that is more struc- turally just in the burdens it imposes on super-rich individuals and corporations, in comparison to the poor (Braithwaite, 2005). Whether we are dealing with tax compliance, nursing home regulation, fraud by major insurance companies, or po- lice threats to the security of a poor community, structural change that conduces to social justice is an emergent possibility from restorative justice innovation. In routine practice, however, structural transformation is rarely a feature of restorative justice (Braithwaite, 2001; White, 2003). According to restorative justice theory, stigmatization of the person as a bad person causes defiance (Ahmed, 2001; Sherman, 1993), perceptions of procedural injustice, refusal to engage with reparative justice, and an increase in reoffending (that increases the amount of injustice in the world). Restorative Justice or Restorative Practices in Civil Society? Wachtel and McCold (2001) conceptualize a continuum of restorative prac- tices. Their most limited restorative intervention is an “affective statement”: “Mary, you sort of hurt my feelings when you did that.” Longer interventions are triggered by “affective questions”: “How do you think Jim felt when you did that?” These Doing Justice Intelligently in Civil Society 401 interventions can be transacted in workplaces, schools, and families on the run, when we encounter people in the corridor. As “affective statements,” they pick up Scheff’s (1994) idea of seeking to expose vulnerable emotions rather than ag- gressive emotions. The next level along Wachtel and McCold’s (2001) restorative practices continuum is a “small impromptu conference.” Informal police cautions can be adapted to this form; the police officer immediately takes a young offender detected of shoplifting home to her parents and all members of the family who are home sit down on the spot to discuss with the police officer what can be done to prevent this from happening again. Finally, the restorative practices continuum can be escalated to circles or conferences of varying composition, degrees of formality, and degrees of ritual significance. And as discussed earlier, larger circles might be broken out into one-on-one mediations in adjournments at various stages of more encompassing community gatherings. Obviously in social life we never have the time or resources for fully fledged restorative processes day by day. Nevertheless, we can learn why an affective question like “How do you think Jim felt when you did that?” is more restorative than yelling at or lecturing a child with: “You’re a naughty boy for doing that to Jim.” Wachtel and McCold favor restorative practices as a more general conceptual- ization of what they study and practice than restorative justice. For them restorative practices are about restoring relationships or social capital, where social capital is conceived as connections among people, trust, and mutual understanding that makes cooperative problem solving possible (Putnam, 2000). Because restoring connectedness is a step toward restoring justice in restorative justice theories, restorative practices should also be directly useful for building social capital in civil society. The disparate range of restorative practices to which Roche (this issue) refers—from Hawkins’ (2002) discussion of negotiated corporate regula- tion to Alternative Dispute Resolution—might be conceived as not fundamentally about justice much of the time. For example, the South African Truth and Reconcil- iation philosophy of ubuntu is described by Roche through the words of Desmond Tutu as “the restoration of broken relationships.” As Roche also points out, it is important to be culturally plural about how we think about the substance of what is being called restorative justice in this issue. Hence, if in a particular cultural con- text there is more resonance, identity affirmation, and pragmatic problem solving in conceiving of family group decision making as about relationships rather than justice, why not do so? This leads us in the next section to consider in more detail family group decision making in Pennell’s (this issue) work, which might equally be conceived as about promoting justice or as about strengthening relationships in civil society ( just as Morrison’s (this issue) work might be as well conceived in a frame of promoting connectedness as promoting justice). For the social scientist, there can be empirical resolution of these conceptual dilemmas. There is a well-developed literature on how to measure social capital arising from the work of Putnam (2000) 402 Braithwaite and others, just as there is a sophisticated literature on perceptual measures of justice from the scholarship of Tyler (this issue) and others. Models can be built where the size of social capital effects and justice effects are put in contest in explaining phenomena like the recovery of victims from trauma and the desistance of perpetrators. But it might be that the big story here is also more holistic. There can be no justice in a world without connectedness and empathy; at the same time, social capital cannot flourish in a world without an infrastructure of security around human relationships that can only be guaranteed by institutions of justice. This relational way of thinking about holistic justice (Burnside & Baker, 1994) is not new. As Strang et al. (this issue) point out, it was a major theme in the Scottish enlightenment, from David Hume’s writings about justice, which give prominence to empathy, to Adam Smith (1790) in his writing on sympathy. Recent neuroscience suggests that the Scottish Enlightenment thinkers may have been right in seeing empathy as inherent to being human, and as a guarantee of the justice that allows us to survive without killing one another. Singer et al. (2004) report that the ability to appreciate the agony of others lights up the same parts of the brain that we use to feel pain ourselves. Feeling our own pain and feeling the pain of others may be embedded in the same elements of a biology that makes humans fit for survival. In contexts of obligation, we have learnt to conceptualize feeling our own pain and feeling the pain of others as feeling unjustly treated and empathizing with injustice done to others. Strength-Based Strategies for Holistic Justice and Connectedness Pennell’s (this issue) essay can be read as showing that one of the things families do in family group conferences to deal with child protection issues is to formulate a care and protection plan that can tie together various strands of support and meaning in civil society networks. An aunt might agree to meet and talk with a child on a weekly basis to check that she has been getting regular cooked meals. If she finds the child is still going hungry, she might sign off an obligation under the plan to report this to a state social worker (binding a strand of family support to one of state control). The plan might import strands of meaning on commitments to the rights of children that come from state laws that have in turn been shaped by the United Nations children’s rights regime. The plan is a little knot that ties together in words that make local sense to the family these national and global strands of meaning. On this view, the family group conference is not guilty of privatizing public issues. Rather, it transmits public issues into private space. Moreover, the knot that ties the aunt into reporting to the state a failure in the conversational regulation of the child’s right to nourishment, is a tie that binds the family to make its private problem a public issue in circumstances of self-regulatory failure. The strengths-based philosophy of the kinds of family group decision making that Pennell has worked with (Burford & Pennell, 1998) is of particular interest Doing Justice Intelligently in Civil Society 403 from the perspective of nodal governance in civil society (Aral et al., 2002). It is about making nodes of local, mostly extended family, governance strong. Pennell points out that taking strengths seriously can be systematic in a facilitation process that asks families as a first step to list their strengths on pieces of paper. But the strengths-based philosophy can be insinuated rather than institutionalized into the family group decision-making process. The point is to educate participants to try to solve problems by building out from their existing strengths. This is the path to hope and pride in nodal capacity building. Burford and Pennell’s (1998) data indeed show that family pride is one of the outcomes better accomplished by these conferences compared to control cases. Private family time, where state professionals leave the room is also, in the Pennell view, a way of signifying where the strength lies to solve the problems at issue. Her North Carolina data show that private family time was not domi- nated by professionals but by family members. Private family time is also about empowerment of the family as a decision-making node in civil society. Belgian conferencing practice, which I recently had an opportunity to observe, may be better here in the way it institutionalizes an adjournment in the full conference for “private time” rather than “private family time.” This empowers participants to constitute whatever nodes of private plan formulation they want; these nodes might be narrower or wider than the boundaries of the family as they choose, or they might be both narrower (e.g., dyadic) and wider at different moments during the private time adjournment. As Pennell points out, the results are encouraging that this form of nodal governance reduces child maltreatment, holds families together in conditions of enhanced pride in their strengths, and reduces domestic violence. Returning to our wider conception of holism, this encourages the inference that family group decision making simultaneously and reciprocally nurtures justice and connectedness. Shame and Restorative Justice Why does Thomas Scheff (1994) seem to be on to something when he says that it is the open expression of the vulnerable emotions in restorative justice processes—such as shame, fear, and grief—as opposed to aggressive emotions— such as anger, rage, and self-righteous indignation—that promote sequences of remorse and forgiveness? Strang’s (2002) quantitative and qualitative data are con- sistent with a picture of anger begetting more anger, but of vulnerable emotions like remorse in one participant begetting vulnerable emotions like forgiveness in another. Restorative justice is about flipping vicious circles of hurt beget- ting hurt into virtuous circles of healing begetting healing. In this, Scheff finds shame to be a particularly important vulnerable emotion, quoting Helen Lynd’s (1958) clinical insight: “the very fact that shame is an isolating experience also 404 Braithwaite means that if one can find ways of sharing and communicating it, this communi- cation can bring about particular closeness with others.” He also makes the point that because the painful emotion of shame is a cross-cultural universal, it is the stuff of powerful intercultural communication when verbal communication fails us. This is true of forgiveness too: the way soldiers move each other with the offer of a hand or a cigarette, surrounded by their mutual slaughter, as they take their dead behind their trenches. Gestures of forgiveness by enemy soldiers show that forgiveness can heal without being preceded by remorse. I have seen this quite often in conferences—victim forgiveness extended to a lost young person who is a remorseless offender, and then the forgiveness elicits remorse. This is actually a reversal of Scheff’s core sequence of remorse eliciting forgiveness, while instan- tiating his more fundamental insight that laying open one vulnerable emotion can trigger reciprocation with another vulnerable emotion. Ahmed and Braithwaite’s (this issue) AMOS analyses cast the most rigorous light to date on the partial va- lidity of both the core remorse to forgiveness (and reconciliation) sequence and the reverse forgiveness and reconciliation to remorse sequence. Scheff’s big insight is Humean—when we see others express painful as opposed to aggressive emotions, we see them as human beings like ourselves. Empathy and compassion thus pave the path to healing. Stigmatization blocks that path. Here there is an interesting connection with Harris’s (this issue) data. He reports a strong positive correlation between his measure of shame–guilt by of- fenders during conferences and empathy on their part. Shame–guilt was also neg- atively correlated with anger/hostility, while “unresolved shame” was positively correlated with anger/hostility. Harris argues that reintegrative shaming may be important for reducing crime not because it results in shame “but because it pro- vides a mechanism that assists offenders to manage their feeling of shame in more constructive ways.” This is consistent with Scheff’s conclusion that when someone has been arrested by the police, the situation is already dripping with shame; the question is whether the shame will be covered over or acknowledged and dealt with. Ahmed/Braithwaite and Morrison take this shame management perspective much further in their contributions to the special issue. We have learnt from experience with restorative justice that shame and pride management skills are not so rare among ordinary members of the community and that the questions observed to routinely succeed in eliciting vulnerable rather than aggressive emotions are quite simple. “How did you feel when you realized your purse was gone?” “How did you feel when the police took you home to tell mum and dad what had happened?” Or when the victim explains how she was hurt by the crime, asking the offender: “What do you think about what happened to me?” A major debate among restorative justice administrators is whether facilitators should be trained to follow a script to ensure that these are the kinds of questions that are always asked, as opposed to questions that might be more likely to elicit Doing Justice Intelligently in Civil Society 405 aggressive emotions. Another reason some defend script-based training is to pre- vent facilitators descending into lecturing of wrongdoers, especially if they are police or youth justice officials who must unlearn lifetime habits of telling young offenders what to do. Of course the argument against scripting is that it inhibits flexibility, responsiveness to cultural difference, and the greater authenticity of more spontaneous forms of communication such as humor, which can be such an asset in tense encounters for those who have the gift to use it without offense. We need to be more evidence-based in this debate, as in many others within restora- tive practice. Randomized controlled trials with assignment to scripted versus unscripted facilitation are needed. In advance of that, we need more systematic naturalistic research that correlates different forms of facilitator questions with responses coded as expressions of aggressive and vulnerable emotion. Pennell’s (this issue) data show that at a more general level, preparation for conferences is important, poor preparation being associated with subsequent ma- nipulation as opposed to empowerment. It may be that Pennell’s valoration of greeting (Young, 1995) at the opening of care and protection conferences—for ex- ample, by prayer, sharing children’s photographs—is another example of a tech- nology of deliberation that conduces to the expression of vulnerable emotions. Again, however, this is an example of an eminently researchable hypothesis that is yet to be tested. Harris’s contribution to this issue shows that criminal offenders randomly assigned to restorative justice conferences perceived others as more disapproving of what they had done, more reintegrative and less stigmatizing than offenders randomly assigned to a criminal trial. Harris finds different kinds of shame-related emotions to be elicited by criminal trials versus conferences. Trials elicit more unresolved shame and more embarrassment exposure, while restorative justice conferences elicit more shame–guilt. Ahmed, Braithwaite, and Morrison (this issue), on data sets from Bangladesh and Australia respectively, both show that shame displacement (blaming others and directing anger toward them) is a shame management strategy that predicts bullying. In contrast, in both studies shame acknowledgment (accepting that wrong was done and moving on from remorse to repair) is a shame management style associated with lower levels of bullying. Replicating another study by Ahmed (2001), Morrison finds that students who were neither bullies nor victims of bul- lying managed shame through shame acknowledgment (taking responsibility and making amends) and were less likely to resort to shame displacement (blaming others and externalizing anger). Picking up concepts from Tyler’s work, Morri- son also found that non-bully non-victims also reported higher levels of pride in membership of the school community and respect within the school. In an interesting way, these shame and pride management strategies of the non-bully non-victims are contrasted with the rather different shame and pride management pathologies of both bullies and victims of bullying. Bullies displace 406 Braithwaite shame into anger without acknowledging shame. Sadly, children who are both bullies and victims end up with the shame management pathologies of both. Bully– victims both attack others and attack themselves (Nathanson, 1997). Morrison points out that we see this with the horrific cases of children who have been bullied at school and respond by perpetrating massacres at the school and then suicide. An important contribution Morrison makes is bringing to bear an integration of Scheff’s theory of unacknowledged shame with reintegrative shaming theory and Tyler’s procedural justice theory in accounting for these phenomena. Morrison has an interesting analysis of victims of bullying as caught up in cycles of persistent shame. On Scheff’s (1994) account, they suffer the form of alienation called engulfment. This means an overemphasis on the “we” of who we are, an “I” engulfed by a “we” to which we feel overly beholden. Morrison’s interpretation of bullies as characterized by the form of alienation Scheff calls isolation—excessive emphasis of the “I” and rejection of the “we”—seems less persuasive. It may be that bullies are alienated from the wider culture of the school yet engulfed by a delinquent subculture. There is some empirical support for Cohen’s (1955) theory of delinquency as a rejection of ones rejectors (Braithwaite, 1989: pp. 21–27). Children who fail in the status system of the school have a status problem that they solve collectively with other children who have been similarly rejected by the status system of the school. They solve it collectively by constituting a delinquent subculture with values that invert those of the school—for example toughness instead of control of aggression, contempt for property instead of respect for property. By inverting the school’s values, rejected children collectively create a subculture that interprets them as a success rather than a failure. On this account, violent children follow a trajectory of isolation from the “we” of the school, then engulfment by the “we” of the anti-school gang. Beyond the effects of shame acknowledgement and shame displacement in re- ducing and increasing bullying, respectively, both forgiveness and reconciliation (restoring relationships with mutual respect) in parental child-rearing practices predicted lower levels of bullying. Notwithstanding this impact of forgiveness and reconciliation on subsequent bullying, there is a strong case for placing forgiveness and reconciliation as secondary objectives of restorative justice. Forgiveness, and more broadly, reconciling, is a gift. If we promote restorative justice programs as having the objective of eliciting forgiveness, we may give victims of bullying and other wrongs the feeling that they are expected to forgive. Any such expec- tation undermines the power of forgiveness because it strips it of the generosity and compassionate spontaneity that gives forgiveness its special meaning as a gift from the wronged to the wrongdoer. We can apply the same analysis to apology. Mandating apology denudes its power as a gift from the person who places them- selves as wrongdoer by apologizing to the wronged. If we apologize because we are required to, the apology ceases to be a manifestation of a vulnerable emotion. We distrust a coerced apology as insincere, as papering over a deeper truth of Doing Justice Intelligently in Civil Society 407 aggressive emotion. In practice, restorative justice programs that do not set out with the direct objective of eliciting forgiveness and apology roughly double the prospects of both and also quadruple prospects that apologies which are given will be perceived as sincere by victims (Sherman et al., 1998; Strang, 2002, Strang et al., this issue). As with shame and remorse as manifestations of vulnerable emotion, so with forgiveness, reconciliation, and apology: if we directly seek to maximize them, we may destroy their power for good. Restorative justice institu- tions pursue open expression of vulnerable emotion indirectly by creating spaces with a minimum of domination and a maximum of support from loved ones. This is what encourages people to take risks with articulating their vulnerability. Conclusion It is early days in research and development on restorative justice. Research has lagged behind theory and theory behind practice. Even so, Strang and Sherman’s (2005) Campbell Collaboration Review of face to face restorative justice refers to 15 randomized controlled trials, of which only 7 are complete. The Latimer et al. (2001) meta-analysis, which included both experiments and non-experimental studies with satisfactory control groups was able to include 32 studies. Moreover, the explosion of experimental and non-experimental research takes off from a pre- existing foundation of multivariate research showing, as Tyler (this issue) points out, that deterrence effects are consistently small in magnitude, that perceived pro- cedural justice effects are stronger, that extrinsic motivations “crowd out” intrinsic motivations to do justice, that punitive parenting is counterproductive. Restorative justice program development has in some important senses aimed at designing justice innovations that apply this research to finding an alternative to regulatory institutions based on Benthamite rational actor presumptions. Sherman (2003) conceives this challenge (see Morrison, this issue) as devel- oping a new paradigm of “emotionally intelligent justice.” The articles in this issue all make important contributions to thinking about justice in terms of nurturing emotional intelligence. They also contribute to seeing conflicts over injustice as opportunities to empower people to learn how to learn in civil society. We live in a world where if justice is to be an accomplishment of our civilization, it will be more an accomplishment of civil society than the state. Certainly, the evidence now seems clear that top-down punitive state justice has limited reach and efficacy. In juxtaposition, all we can say of restorative justice is that it shows promise and, as this special issue illustrates, is engendering a kaleidoscope of institutional in- novation. There is a long way to go before we can be evidence-based about which of the colors in the restorative justice rainbow really do enrich justice. There is even further to travel before we discover whether those colors can come together to form a bright white light to lead us from the darkness of the Guantanamo Bays and the school exclusion policies of this world. 408 Braithwaite References Ahmed, E. (2001). Shame management: Regulating bullying. In E. Ahmed, N. Harris, J. Braithwaite, & V. Braithwaite (Eds.), Shame management through reintegration (pp. 211–314). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Angel, C. (2005). Crime victims meet their offenders: Testing the impact of restorative justice confer- ences on victims’ post-traumatic stress symptoms. PhD dissertation, University of Pennsylvania. Aral, S., Burris, S., & Shearing, C. (2002). Health and the governance of security: A tale of two systems. The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics, 304, 632–643. Barnes, G. (1999). Procedural justice in two contexts: Testing the fairness of diversionary conferenc- ing for intoxicated drivers. Unpublished PhD dissertation, Institute of Criminal Justice and Criminology, University of Maryland. Bazemore, G., & Schiff, M. (2005). Juvenile justice reform and restorative justice. Portland, OR: Willan Publishing. Bonta, J., Jesseman, R., Rugge, T., & Cormier, R. (2006). Restorative justice and recidivism: Promises made, promises kept? In D. Sullivan & L. Tifft (Eds.), Handbook of restorative justice: A global perspective. London: Routledge. Braithwaite, J. (1989). Crime, shame and reintegration. Melbourne: Cambridge University Press. Braithwaite, J. (2001). Restorative justice and social justice. Saskatchewan Law Review, 63, 185– 194. Braithwaite, J. (2002). Restorative justice and responsive regulation. New York: Oxford University Press. Braithwaite, J. (2005). Markets in vice, markets in virtue. New York: Oxford Univeristy Press. Burford, G., & Pennell, J. (1998). Family group decision making project: Outcome report Volume I. St. John’s: Memorial University, Newfoundland. Burnside, J., & Baker, N. (1994). Relational justice: Repairing the breach. Winchester: Waterside Press. Cohen, A. K. (1955). Delinquent boys: The culture of the gang. Glencoe, IL: Free Press. Collins, R. (2004). Interaction ritual chains. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Hawkins, K. (2002). Law as last resort: Prosecution decision-making in a regulatory agency. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Latimer, J., Dowden, C., & Muise, D. (2001). The effectiveness of restorative justice practices: A meta-analysis. Ottawa: Department of Justice, Canada. Leventhal, G. S. (1980). What should be done with equity theory? New approaches to the study of fairness in social relationships. In K. Gergen, M. Greenberg, & R. Willis (Eds.), Social exchanges: Advances in theory and research (pp. 27–55). New York: Plenum. Lind, E. A., & Tyler, T. R. (1988). The social psychology of procedural justice. New York: Plenum Press. Lynd, H. (1958). On shame and the search for identity. New York: Harcourt. Maxwell, G. M., & Morris, A. (1993). Family, victims and culture: Youth justice in New Zealand. New Zealand: Social Policy Agency and Institute of Criminology, Victoria University of Wellington. Nathanson, D. L. (1997). Affect theory and the compass of shame. In M. R. Lansky (Ed.), The widening scope of shame. Hillsdale, NJ: The Analytic Press. Putnam, R. (2000). Bowling alone: The collapse and revival of American community. New York: Simon Schuster. Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Roche, D. (2003). Accountability in restorative justice. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Scheff, T. J. (1994). Bloody revenge: Emotions, nationalism and war. Boulder, CO: Westview Press. Sherman, L. W. (1993). Defiance, deterrence and irrelevance: A theory of the criminal sanction. Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency, 30, 445–473. Sherman, L. W. (2003). Reason for emotion: Reinventing justice with theories, innovations, and re- search. The American Society of Criminology, 2002 Presidential Address. Criminology, 41, 1–38. Sherman, L. W., Strang, H., Barnes, G., Braithwaite, J., Inkpen, N., & Teh, M. M. (1998). Experiments in restorative policing: A progress report on the Canberra Reintegrative Shaming Experiments Doing Justice Intelligently in Civil Society 409 (RISE). Canberra: Law Program, Research School of Social Sciences, Australian National University. Singer, T., Seymour, B., O’Doherty, J., Kaube, H., Dolan, R.J., & Forth, C. D. (2004). Empathy for pain involves the affective but not sensory components of pain. Science, 303, 1157– 1162. Smith, A. (1790). The theory of the moral sentiments. London: A. Millar. Strang, H. (2002). Victim participation in a restorative justice process. New York: Oxford University Press. Strang, H., & Sherman, L. W. (2005). Effects of face-to-face restorative justice for personal victim crimes. Campbell Collaboration Review. Available at www.campbellcollaboration.org. Tutu, D. (1999). No future without forgiveness. London: Rider. Tyler, T. (1990). Why people obey the law. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Tyler, T., & Blader, S. (2000). Cooperation in groups: Procedural justice, social identity, and behavioral engagement. Philadelphia, PA: Psychology Press. Tyler, T., & Dawes, R. M. (1993). Fairness in groups: Comparing the self-interest and social identity perspectives. In B. A. Mellers & J. Baron (Eds.), Psychological perspectives on justice: Theory and applications. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Tyler, T., & Huo, Y. J. (2001). Trust and the rule of law: A law-abidingness model of social control. New York: Russel Sage. Wachtel, T., & McCold, P. (2001). Restorative justice in everyday life. In H. Strang & J. Braithwaite (Eds.), Restorative justice and civil society. Melbourne: Cambridge University Press. Wenzel, M. (2000). Justice and identity: The significance of inclusion for perceptions of entitlement and the justice motive. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 26, 157–176. Wenzel, M. (2002). The impact of outcome orientation and justice concerns on tax compliance: The role of taxpayers’ identity. Journal of Applied Psychology, 87, 629–645. White, R. (2003). Communities, conferences and restorative social justice. Criminal Justice, 2, 139– 160. Young, I. (1995). Communication and the other: Beyond deliberative democracy. In M. Wilson & A. Yeatman (Eds.), Justice and identity: Antipodean practices. Wellington, New Zealand: Bridget Williams Books. Zehr, H. (1995). Changing lenses: A new focus for criminal justice. Scottdale, PA: Herald Press. JOHN BRAITHWAITE is Professor and Australian Research Council Federa- tion Fellow in the Regulatory Institutions Network at the Australian National University. Among his recent publications are Markets in Vice, Markets in Virtue (2005), Restorative Justice and Responsive Regulation (2002), and Shame Man- agement through Reintegration (2001). work_3pkxo2l5nnco7ohssf2635rqem ---- wp-p1m-39.ebi.ac.uk Params is empty 404 sys_1000 exception wp-p1m-39.ebi.ac.uk no 221729108 Params is empty 221729108 exception Params is empty 2021/04/06-03:20:25 if (typeof jQuery === "undefined") document.write('[script type="text/javascript" src="/corehtml/pmc/jig/1.14.8/js/jig.min.js"][/script]'.replace(/\[/g,String.fromCharCode(60)).replace(/\]/g,String.fromCharCode(62))); // // // window.name="mainwindow"; .pmc-wm {background:transparent repeat-y top left;background-image:url(/corehtml/pmc/pmcgifs/wm-nobrand.png);background-size: auto, contain} .print-view{display:block} Page not available Reason: The web page address (URL) that you used may be incorrect. Message ID: 221729108 (wp-p1m-39.ebi.ac.uk) Time: 2021/04/06 03:20:25 If you need further help, please send an email to PMC. Include the information from the box above in your message. Otherwise, click on one of the following links to continue using PMC: Search the complete PMC archive. Browse the contents of a specific journal in PMC. Find a specific article by its citation (journal, date, volume, first page, author or article title). http://europepmc.org/abstract/MED/ work_3turivdnmvggjb2msf6xw74azy ---- Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 U.S. Department of Justice Office of Justice Programs Bureau of Justice Statistics BJS Mandatory P.L. 280 states Optional P.L. 280 states Indian reservations (U.S. Census Bureau) Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics Overview Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities Duren Banks, Steven W. Perry, and Allina Lee Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 Brian Reaves State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 Steven W. Perry, Ron Malega, and Duren Banks Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 Todd Minton Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System Mark Motivans and Howard Snyder Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 2 June 2011 Bureau of Justice Statistics James P. Lynch Director BJS Website: www.bjs.gov For information contact: BJS Clearinghouse 1-800-732-3277 The Bureau of Justice Statistics is the statistics agency of the U.S. Department of Justice. Duren Banks coordinated the development of this compendium. Contributing authors include Duren Banks, Allina Lee, Ron Malega, Todd Minton, Mark Motivans, Steven W. Perry, Brian Reaves, and Howard Snyder. In addition to the authors, other BJS staff who contributed to verification include Paul Guerino, Tracey Kyckelhahn, and Tracy L. Snell. Morgan Young and Jill Thomas edited the report, Barbara Quinn designed and produced the report, and Jayne Robinson and Tina Dorsey prepared the report for final printing under the supervision of Doris J. James. June 2011, NCJ 234459 3Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 BJS Mandatory P.L. 280 states Optional P.L. 280 states Indian reservations (U.S. Census Bureau) Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics Overview Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities Duren Banks, Steven W. Perry, and Allina Lee Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 Brian Reaves State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 Steven W. Perry, Ron Malega, and Duren Banks Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 Todd Minton Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System Mark Motivans and Howard Snyder 4 June 2011 Content s Overview 7 Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities 9 The Tribal Law and Order Act, 2010 (TLOA; Pub. L. No. 111-211, 124 Stat. 2258, Section 251(b)) requires the Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS) to establish and implement a tribal data collection system and to support tribal participation in national records and information systems. This is the first BJS report on the status of tribal data collection activities as required by the act. It describes BJS’s activities between July 2010 and June 2011 to improve tribal law enforcement reporting to the FBI’s Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) and BJS’s direct collaboration with tribal criminal justice systems to collect data about tribal court systems. It summarizes data published by BJS on jails in Indian country, tribal law enforcement agencies, state prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction in Indian country, tribal youth in the federal justice system, and reporting to the UCR. It describes activities and funding opportunities to improve tribal crime data collection through programs such as the National Criminal History Improvement Program (NCHIP), the National Instant Criminal Background Check System (NICS), Byrne/JAG funding, and UCR training. Table 1.1. Tribes submitting crime data to the Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) Program and receiving Byrne/Justice Assistance Grant (JAG) awards, FY 2008-2010 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10 Table 1.2. Bureau of Justice Statistics planned program activities in response to the Tribal Law and Order Act . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 13 Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 15 Presents data on tribal law enforcement agencies from the 2008 Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies. This report defines the number and locations of tribal law enforcement agencies, service populations, and the number of sworn and nonsworn employees. It describes agency participation in traditional law enforcement (routine patrol, criminal investigation, and dispatching calls for service), public safety functions (emergency management, animal control, and fire services), specialized functions (search and rescue, tactical operations, and underwater recovery), and court-related activities (executing arrest warrants, enforcing protection orders, and serving process). The report details participation in multiagency task forces involving drug and human trafficking, gangs, violent crime, and antiterrorism. It presents data on community outreach efforts, such as school resource officers and community policing officers. Table 2.1. Tribally operated law enforcement agencies, by type of agency and number of full-time sworn personnel, 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 16 Table 2.2. The 25 largest tribally operated law enforcement agencies, by the number of full-time sworn personnel, 2008. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17 Table 2.3. Use of community policing and school resource officers by tribal police departments, 2000 and 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 18 Figure 2.1. Location of tribally operated law enforcement agencies, 2008 . 15 Figure 2.2. Selected law enforcement functions performed by tribal police departments, 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 18 Figure 2.3. Selected court-related functions performed by tribal police departments, 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 18 Figure 2.4. Selected special functions performed by tribal police departments, 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 19 Figure 2.5. Task force participation of tribal police departments, 2008 . . . 19 State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 21 Describes state prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction in Indian country under Public Law 83-280 (P.L. 280). This report examines the activities of prosecutors’ offices in states affected by P.L. 280 through either mandatory or optional jurisdiction. Six states have mandatory jurisdiction under P.L. 280 over crimes in Indian country: Alaska, California, Minnesota (except the Red Lake Reservation), Nebraska, Oregon (except the Warm Springs Reservation), and Wisconsin. The report also examines activities of prosecutors’ offices in the 10 states that have an option to assume jurisdiction over crimes in Indian country within their borders: Arizona, Florida, Idaho, Iowa, Montana, Nevada, North Dakota, South Dakota, Utah, and Washington. Using data from the 2007 National Census of State Court Prosecutors, this report describes the characteristics of state prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction for crimes committed in Indian country, including budgets, staffing, and caseload. It also examines the types of offenses committed in Indian country that were prosecuted in 2007. Table 3.1. Number of tribes participating in the Census of Tribal Justice Agencies in Indian Country, by P.L. 280 status, type of court systems, and state, 2002 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 22 Table 3.2. State prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction for crimes committed in Indian country, by P.L. 280 status, 2007 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 22 Table 3.3. Type of state prosecutors’ offices in Indian country, by P.L. 280 status, 2007. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 25 Table 3.4. Budget, staffing, and caseload of state prosecutors’ offices, by P.L. 280 status, 2007 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 25 Figure 3.1. State prosecutors’ offices reporting jurisdiction in Indian country under P.L. 280, 2007 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 23 Figure 3.2. State prosecutors’ offices reporting prosecution of specific crimes in Indian country, by P.L. 280 status, 2007 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 24 5Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 Contents (continued) Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 27 Presents selected findings from the bulletin Jails in Indian Country, 2009, released in February 2011 (NCJ232223). Data are based on an enumeration of 80 jails, confinement facilities, detention centers, and other facilities operated by tribal authorities or the Bureau of Indian Affairs (BIA) reported to the annual Survey of Jails in Indian Country. The report includes data on the number of adults and juveniles held, type of offense, number of persons confined on the last weekday of each month, average daily population, peak population, and admissions in June 2009. It also summarizes rated capacity, facility crowding, and jail staffing. Table 4.1. Inmates, rated capacity, and percent of capacity occupied in Indian country jails, 2004 and 2007-2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 28 Table 4.2. Jails in Indian country that held the majority of inmates in 2009 compared to 2008, by facility . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 28 Table 4.3. Number of Indian country jails, by percent of rated capacity occupied, June 2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 29 Table 4.4. Admissions and expected length of stay in Indian country jails during June, by facility size, June 2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 30 Table 4.5. Number of inmates confined in Indian country jails, by demographic characteristics, conviction status, and offense, midyear 2000, 2002, 2004, and 2007-2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 31 Table 4.6. Number of persons employed in Indian country jails, by job function, June 30, 2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 32 Figure 4.1. Inmates confined in Indian country jails, at midyear 2000-2004 and 2007-2009. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 27 Figure 4.2. Percent of rated capacity occupied, by type of inmate count, June 2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 29 Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 35 Presents findings on tribal youth processed through the federal criminal justice system between 1999 and 2008. Findings are from a recent study conducted by the Urban Institute under the Bureau of Justice Statistics’ Federal Justice Statistics Program (FJSP). This report describes the number of tribal youth in the federal system and examines how they are handled through the stages of the federal criminal case process, from arrest to confinement. It describes tribal youth demographic characteristics, offenses, and case outcomes, such as referrals for prosecution, dismissal rates, sentencing, and time served. Table 5.1. Reason for matters declined for prosecution with tribal youth suspects, 2005-2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 37 Table 5.2. Federally recognized tribes and enrolled members, 2005. . . . . 38 Table 5.3. Tribal and non-tribal youth admitted to the Federal Bureau of Prisons, by offense type, 1944-2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 41 Figure 5.1. Tribal youth referred to and prosecuted by U.S. attorneys, 2000-2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 35 Figure 5.2. Case-related reasons for declination, 2005-2008 . . . . . . . . . 37 Figure 5.3. Tribal youth admitted to the custody of federal prison authorities, and five federal judicial districts that committed the majority of tribal youth, 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 38 Figure 5.4. Maximum time in federal custody of juveniles adjudicated delinquent . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 39 Figure 5.5. Tribal youth in the Federal Bureau of Prisons, by status, at admission, 2000-2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40 Figure 5.6. Non-tribal youth admitted to the Federal Bureau of Prisons, by status, at admission, 2000-2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40 Figure 5.7. Non-tribal youth admitted to the custody of federal prison authorities, and five federal judicial districts that committed the majority of tribal youth, 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 42 Highlights Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities 9 � The Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS) consulted with tribal leaders through a variety of forums in 2010. � For the first time, the Bureau of Indian Affairs’ (BIA) submissions to the Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) were disaggregated by tribe and reported in Crime in the U.S., 2009. � The number of tribes eligible for Byrne/JAG funding increased from 5 to 22. � In 2008, 140 tribal law enforcement staff received UCR training. � BJS provided competitive funding opportunities for jurisdictions to improve criminal records. � BJS developed a multifaceted data collection system that both established new collections and enhanced current programs. 6 June 2011 Highlights (continued) Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 15 � Tribally operated law enforcement agencies employed nearly 4,600 full-time personnel, including about 3,000 sworn officers. � The largest tribal law enforcement agency, the Navajo Police Department, employed 393 full-time sworn personnel in Arizona, New Mexico, and Utah. � Eleven of the 25 largest tribal law enforcement agencies served jurisdictions covering more than 1,000 square miles. � Overall, tribal police departments cost about $257 per resident to operate during fiscal year 2008. � In addition to law enforcement functions, nearly all tribal police departments performed court-related functions, such as court security and serving process. � More than half of tribal police departments used community policing officers, and more than a third used school resource officers. � About 4 in 5 tribal police departments participated in one or more multiagency task forces. State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 21 � Ninety-three state court prosecutors’ offices in the 16 P.L. 280 states reported jurisdiction for felonies committed in Indian country under P.L. 280. � Seventy-three percent of offices with jurisdiction in Indian country reported prosecuting at least one felony case committed in Indian country. � Most offices in P.L. 280 states prosecuted at least one offense involving drugs (63%), domestic violence (60%), or aggravated assault (58%). � Eighteen offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states with jurisdiction for Indian country prosecuted at least one rape, and 12 offices prosecuted a homicide. � Of state prosecutors’ offices that reported jurisdiction for felony cases in Indian country under P.L. 280, 70% served judicial districts with populations of less than 100,000 residents. � Offices with jurisdiction for felony crimes committed in Indian country had an average operating budget of $5.2 million in 2007. Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 27 � The number of inmates confined in Indian country jails increased by 1.9% between midyear 2008 and 2009, reaching 2,176 inmates. � Between June 2008 and June 2009, the average daily jail population in Indian country increased by 12%, and the percentage of occupied bed space increased from 64.2% to 73.5%. � Eleven jails (14% of all facilities) held 51% of inmates confined at midyear 2009. � During June 2009, the number of inmates admitted to Indian country jails (11,357) was about 5 times the size of the average daily population (2,124). � The expected average length of stay increased by a half day from 5.1 days during June 2008 to 5.6 days during June 2009. � Indian country jail authorities reported no deaths in custody between July 1, 2008, and June 30, 2009, down from 4 reported deaths during the 12-month period ending June 30, 2008. � Attempted suicides by inmates declined from 78 in 2008 to 56 in 2009. � Indian country jails held fewer inmates for domestic violence at midyear 2009 (252), continuing the downward trend in the number held for this offense since 2007 (362). � The percentage of certified correctional officers working in Indian country jails increased steadily, from 63% at midyear 2007 to 79% at midyear 2009. Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 35 � In 2008, relatively few juveniles were referred to federal prosecutors (315 out of 178,570 suspects) or admitted to federal prison jurisdiction (156 out 71,663 offenders). � Tribal youth (70) comprised nearly half of juveniles (152) handled by the federal courts in 2008. � Federal judicial districts of Arizona, Montana, South Dakota, New Mexico, and North Dakota accounted for 94% of tribal youth investigated, 92% of those prosecuted, and 88% of those admitted to federal prison jurisdiction in 2008. � In 2008, about 72% of tribal youth were investigated for violent offenses, including sexual abuse (35%), assault (20%), and murder (17%). � About 40% of matters involving tribal youth were declined by federal prosecutors in 2008. � A greater share of cases involving tribal youth in U.S. district courts were terminated by conviction (91%) than by dismissal (9%). � From 1994 to 2008, the lowest number of tribal (72) and non-tribal youth (84) admitted to the jurisdiction of federal prison authorities occurred in 2008. � Admissions to federal prison jurisdiction among tribal youth declined 10% per year from 1999 to 2008, while non-tribal youth admissions declined 12% per year. � In 2008, tribal youth served an average of 26 months under federal jurisdiction, which was more than double the tribal justice system maximum sentence of 12 months. 7Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 Overview The Tribal Law and Order Act (TLOA), enacted July 29, 2010, requires the Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS) to (1) establish and implement a tribal data collection system and (2) support tribal participation in national records and information systems (P.L. 111-211, 124 Stat. 2258, § 251(b)). The act further requires the director of BJS to consult with Indian tribes to establish and implement this data collection system. The BJS director is required to report to Congress within one year of enactment, and annually thereafter, the data collected and analyzed in accordance with the act. This report describes activities in support of BJS’s tribal crime data collection system and summarizes findings published from that system between July 2010 and June 2011. Multifaceted data collection system Criminal jurisdiction in Indian country—federally recognized reservations, tribal communities, and identified trust lands—varies by the type of crime committed, whether the offender or victim was a tribal member, and the state in which the offense occurred. Due to the sovereign status of federally recognized tribes in the United States, crimes committed in Indian country are often subject to concurrent jurisdiction between multiple criminal justice agencies. Public Law 83-280 (P.L. 280) gave select states legal jurisdiction over tribal members to prosecute crimes that occur on the reservation under existing state laws. These mandatory P.L. 280 states include California, Minnesota (except the Red Lake Reservation), Nebraska, Oregon (except the Warm Springs Reservation), Wisconsin, and Alaska. P.L. 280 permitted other states to acquire jurisdiction over crimes committed in Indian country at their option. These optional P.L. 280 states assume jurisdiction, either in whole or in part, over Indian country within their boundaries, and include Arizona, Florida, Idaho, Iowa, Montana, Nevada, North Dakota, South Dakota, Utah, and Washington. In the remaining states, where P.L. 280 does not apply, federal and tribal governments maintain concurrent jurisdiction for major crimes committed in Indian country (as defined in the Major Crimes Act and subsequent amendments (18 U.S.C. § 1153)). Tribal governments have jurisdiction for all other crimes committed in Indian country that involve both an Indian offender and Indian victim. States retain jurisdiction for non-Indian crimes committed in Indian country—those in which neither the offender nor the victim is a tribal member. Due in part to these jurisdictional complexities, existing tribal data systems are often limited in scope and applicable only to certain jurisdictions or states. An effective tribal data collection system will include data from federal, state, local, and tribal agencies. The information maintained in this system should further be considered in light of the concurrent jurisdictional roles multiple agencies maintain in Indian country. Recent findings from the tribal data collection system 178 tribal law enforcement agencies operated in 2008 In September 2008, American Indian tribes operated 178 law enforcement agencies. These 178 agencies employed at least one full-time sworn officer with general arrest powers or the equivalent in part-time officers. The total includes 157 general purpose tribal police departments and 21 special jurisdiction agencies tasked with enforcing natural resources laws that pertain primarily to hunting and fishing on tribal lands. Tribes operated law enforcement agencies in 28 states and employed about 3,000 full-time sworn personnel. Eleven of the 25 largest tribal law enforcement agencies served jurisdictions of more than 1,000 square miles. (See Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008, page 15, for more information.) 83 tribal law enforcement agencies provided data through the Bureau of Indian Affairs (BIA) that met the FBI’s guidelines for publication Offenses known to tribal law enforcement agencies were reported by tribal agencies in the FBI’s Crime in the United States, 2009. Eighty-three tribal law enforcement agencies met FBI guidelines for data publication in the report.* Nearly 3,800 violent crimes and approximately 11,400 property crimes were known to *Crimes known to tribal law enforcement agencies are submitted to the UCR through the BIA. UCR data must be submitted by local law enforcement with a valid reporting number, and be complete for all 12 months of the year. Data submitted to the UCR must also meet FBI data quality guidelines for publication in Crime in the U.S. 8 June 2011 these selected tribal law enforcement agencies in 2009. (See the FBI’s Crime in the United States, 2009, http:// www2.fbi.gov/ucr/cius2009/data/ table_11.html, for more information.) 93 state prosecutors’ offices in P.L. 280 states reported jurisdiction for felonies committed in Indian country In 2007, 93 state court prosecutors’ offices reported jurisdiction under P.L. 280 for felonies committed in Indian country. Seventy-three percent of these offices reported prosecuting at least one felony case that arose from Indian country in 2007, including at least one offense that involved drugs (63%), domestic violence (60%), or aggravated assault (58%). Most state prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction under P.L. 280 served districts with 100,000 or fewer residents. (See State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007, page 21, for more information.) Jails in Indian country housed 2,176 inmates in 2009 The number of inmates confined in Indian country jails increased by 1.9% between midyear 2008 and midyear 2009, from 2,135 to 2,176 inmates. Over the 12 months ending June 2009, the average daily jail population in Indian country increased by 12%, and the percentage of occupied bed space increased from 64.2% to 73.5%. (See Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009, page 27, for more information.) Most tribal youth in the federal system were referred for violent offenses Between 1999 and 2008, 65% of tribal youth in criminal matters received by federal prosecutors were referred for a violent offense. Sexual abuse was the most common violent offense, followed by assault and murder. In 2008, federal prosecutors received 129 tribal youth suspects in matters opened out of 178,570 total matters investigated. Tribal youth admitted to the legal custody of federal prison authorities were mostly male (90%) and tended to be older teens; more than two-thirds were between the ages 16 and 17. (See Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System, page 35, for more information.) 9Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities, 2011 The Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS), in collaboration with other federal agencies and American Indian tribes, conducted several activities to develop the tribal data collection system as of June 2011. The data collection system establishes both new data collections and enhances current programs to carry out the requirements of the Tribal Law and Order Act (TLOA), 2010. BJS focused on improving tribal law enforcement reporting to the FBI’s Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) and developed direct data collection from tribal criminal justice systems, such as collecting information about the nature and operation of tribal court systems. Efforts also include activities and funding opportunities to improve tribal crime data collection through programs such as the National Criminal History Improvement Program (NCHIP), the National Instant Criminal Background Check System (NICS), Byrne/JAG funding, and UCR training. Activities to Support Tribal Crime Data Collection Systems, July 2010 through June 2011 Tribal consultations conducted in 2010 BJS consulted with tribal leaders through a variety of forums in 2010. BJS developed and distributed an initial plan that responded to the TLOA sections that directly referenced tribal crime data collection. This plan was presented to several stakeholder groups to invite feedback and input, including— � Interdepartmental Tribal Justice Safety and Wellness Consultation, Session 12 (December 2010, Palm Springs, CA) � Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) trainings for tribal law enforcement (2010) agencies � National Congress of American Indians, 2011 Executive Council Winter Meeting (March 2011, Washington, DC). For the first time, the Bureau of Indian Affairs’ (BIA) submissions to UCR were disaggregated by tribe and reported in the FBI’s Crime in the U.S., 2009 Working with the Office of Justice Services in the BIA, and the Office of Tribal Justice and the FBI in the Department of Justice (DOJ), BJS developed a process to support tribal access to, and input in, regional and national criminal justice databases, including the National Crime Information Center (NCIC) and the Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR). As a result of this process, data provided to the FBI from the BIA were able to be disaggregated by tribe. Offenses known to tribal law enforcement agencies were reported by tribal agencies in the FBI’s Crime in the United States, 2009. Eighty- three tribal law enforcement agencies met FBI guidelines for data to be published in the report. Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities, 2011 Duren Banks, Ph.D., and Steven W. Perry, BJS Statisticians Allina Lee, BJS Policy Analyst U.S. Department of Justice Office of Justice Programs Bureau of Justice Statistics June 2011, NCJ 234518 Highlights � The Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS) consulted with tribal leaders through a variety of forums in 2010. � For the first time, the Bureau of Indian Affairs’ (BIA) submissions to the Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) were disaggregated by tribe and reported in Crime in the U.S., 2009. � The number of tribes eligible for Byrne/JAG funding increased from 5 in 2008 to 22 in 2010. � In 2010, 140 tribal law enforcement staff received UCR training. � BJS provided competitive funding opportunities for jurisdictions to improve criminal records in fiscal year 2011. � BJS developed a multifaceted data collection system that both established new collections and enhanced current programs. 10 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 The number of tribes eligible for Byrne/ JAG funding increased from 5 in fiscal year 2008 to 22 in fiscal year 2010 Collaborative efforts between the departments of Justice and Interior have increased the number of tribes reporting monthly crime data to the UCR, thereby increasing the number of tribes eligible to receive Byrne/JAG awards. Byrne/JAG funds can be used to support a range of activities in seven broad program areas, including law enforcement; prosecution and courts; crime prevention and education; corrections; drug treatment and enforcement; program planning, evaluation, and technology improvement; and crime victim and witness programs. Most American Indian tribes had been ineligible to receive Byrne/JAG funds because of gaps in Indian country crime statistics and traditional methods for reporting data. Prior to 2009, BIA provided an aggregate number of crimes known to tribal law enforcement to the UCR. Since these data could not be disaggregated by tribe, tribal law enforcement agencies that did not submit information directly to the UCR were not eligible for Byrne/JAG awards. In FY 2008, 25 tribes submitted crime data directly to the FBI, with 5 of the tribes eligible to receive Byrne/JAG awards totaling $150,000. In FY 2010, the number of tribes that submitted crime data increased to 144 following collaborative efforts between agencies in the departments of Justice and Interior, with 22 tribes eligible for Byrne/JAG awards totaling $709,000 (table 1.1). More than 140 tribal law enforcement staff received UCR training Through Recovery Act funds, BJS developed and implemented the Tribal Crime Data project to further support the reporting of tribal crime to the UCR, and thereby establish eligibility for Byrne/ JAG funds. The project is also part of BJS’s larger effort to collect more reliable information on American Indians in the criminal justice system and crimes committed in Indian country. Through the Tribal Crime Data project, BJS conducted three training sessions in 2010, with more than 140 tribal members, on the use of the UCR systems. In 2011 the project provided training and technical assistance to tribes that did not meet FBI data quality guidelines or had not previously submitted complete crime data to BIA. Table 1.1 Tribes submitting crime data to the Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) and receiving Justice Assistance Grant (JAG) awards, FY 2008–2010 Number of tribes— Fiscal Year Reporting to UCR Eligible for JAG award Eligible award amount 2008 25 5 $150,000 2009 106 20 559,000 2010 144 22 709,000 BJS, acting jointly with the Office of Justice Services, BIA (DOI), and the FBI (DOJ), will work with tribes and tribal law enforcement to establish and implement tribal data collection systems (P.L. 111-211 § 251(b)). 11Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities, 2011 Funding for improving criminal records To improve criminal records, BJS provided outreach to agencies in tribal jurisdictions through two competitive funding opportunities: � National Criminal History Improvement Program (NCHIP) solicitation, 2011 � National Instant Criminal Background Check System (NICS) Act Record Improvement Program (NARIP) solicitation, 2011. The TLOA made federally recognized tribes eligible for awards under BJS’s NCHIP. State and tribal entities apply for NCHIP funds to enhance the crime fighting and criminal justice capabilities of governments by improving the accuracy, utility, and interstate accessibility of criminal history records. Jurisdictions also apply for NCHIP funds to enhance records of protective orders that involve domestic violence and stalking, sex offender records, automated identification systems, and other state systems that support national records systems and their use for criminal history background checks. BJS released the FY 2011 NCHIP solicitation on January 13, 2011, and collaborated with other OJP components to disseminate information about the NCHIP funding announcement as broadly as possible. Tribal contacts were alerted via email to the funding opportunity, and the solicitation was posted to the BJS and DOJ Tribal Safety and Justice websites. Information about the NCHIP funding opportunity was also presented during several meetings and a consultation in the fall and winter of 2010. Additionally, BJS developed an addendum to the solicitation that identified priority funding areas and eligibility requirements for tribal applicants. The addendum outlined key tribal priority areas activities related to— � information technology systems to capture and transmit tribal issued domestic violence and stalking records to the FBI NCIC Protection Order File � automation and transmission of existing qualifying domestic violence and stalking records to the FBI NCIC Protection Order File. The NARIP implements the provisions of the NICS Improvement Amendments Act of 2007, enacted in the wake of the shooting tragedy at Virginia Tech and includes tribes as eligible entities. The NARIP funds provide assistance to eligible states and tribes to improve the completeness, automation, and transmittal of records needed by the NICS to identify persons prohibited from receiving or possessing a firearm. These records include prohibited mental health adjudications and commitments, felony convictions, felony indictments, fugitives from justice, drug arrests and convictions, domestic violence protection orders, and misdemeanor crimes of domestic violence. BJS will award FY 2011 NARIP funds to support efforts to improve the records used by NICS, by providing assistance to states and tribes to improve the completeness, automation, and transmittal of records to state and federal systems. BJS released the FY 2011 NARIP solicitation on March 15, 2011. The same process used to disseminate information about the NCHIP funding opportunity was followed to alert tribes to the NARIP solicitation. Subject to the availability of appropriated funds and any modifications or additional requirements that may be imposed by law, BJS plans to competitively award NCHIP and NARIP funds in FY 2011. Eligible applications will be evaluated and scored by peer reviewers, and funding will be made based on the selection criteria outlined in the solicitations. BJS is authorized to provide for improvements in the accuracy, quality, timeliness, immediate accessibility, and integration of state and tribal criminal history and related records (P.L. 111-211 § 251(b)(1)(H)). 12 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 BJS established new collections and enhanced current programs In addition to collaborating with other federal agencies to improve tribal law enforcement reporting to the UCR, BJS developed a plan to collect information about tribal criminal justice systems. This multipronged approach both established new collections and enhanced current programs that serve the purposes of the TLOA. Through its ongoing statistical projects, BJS provided information on (1) suspects and defendants processed in the federal criminal justice system, including federal prosecutions of crimes committed in Indian country, (2) the incidence of crimes known to law enforcement that occur on tribal reservations or were reported by Indian country law enforcement authorities, (3) the characteristics of tribal law enforcement agencies, and (4) the characteristics of jails in Indian country. BJS plans to begin collecting information about the nature and operation of tribal court systems in 2012 (table 1.2). Survey of Tribal Court Systems BJS developed the Survey of Tribal Court Systems to build on BJS’s previous Census of Tribal Justice Agencies (See Census of Tribal Justice Agencies in Indian Country, 2002, BJS Web, December 2005). The survey will gather administrative and operational information from tribal courts, prosecutors’ offices, and indigent defense providers operating in the estimated 190 federally recognized tribal justice systems in the U.S. Subject to the availability of appropriated funds and any modifications or additional requirements that may be imposed by law, BJS plans to award the Survey of Tribal Court Systems in FY 2011. BJS will work with the awardee and collaborating organizations to develop the data collection instrument and methodology. The instrument will include, at a minimum, measures of tribal court organization, court caseload, characteristics of prosecutors in tribal courts, and systems to provide indigent defense in tribal courts. Based on the results of the initial data collection, BJS will devise a strategy for conducting a regular data collection program among Indian country court systems. Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies The Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies provides data on staffing, functions, and expenditures. Data collected include the number of sworn and civilian personnel by state and type of agency, and functions performed by each agency. BJS analyzed and published findings from data collected in 2008, from the Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies program, including 178 tribal law enforcement agencies. Survey of Jails in Indian Country The Survey of Jails in Indian Country data describe jails, confinement facilities, detention centers, and other facilities operated by tribal authorities or BIA. The annual report from the Survey of Jails in Indian Country includes data on the number of adults and juveniles held, type of offense, number of persons confined on the last weekday of each month, average daily population, peak population, and admissions at midyear. It also summarizes rated capacity, facility crowding, and jail staffing. The most recent report that describes findings from the 2009 survey was released in February 2011. National Census of State Court Prosecutors In 2007 BJS conducted the National Census of State Prosecutors, which was the second complete enumeration of all chief prosecutors who tried felony cases in state courts of general jurisdiction. The census collected information about whether district The director of BJS will establish and implement a tribal data collection system (P.L. 111-211 § 251(b)). 13Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities, 2011 Table 1.2 Bureau of Justice Statistics Planned Program Activities in Response to the Tribal Law and Order Act Program Objective Timeline Collaboration with DOJ Components and BIA To increase the number of tribes eligible to receive Edward Byrne Memorial Justice Assistance Grant (JAG) Program funds, ensure tribal access to regional and national databases, and develop comprehensive tribal crime data systems. Ongoing. BJS Recovery Act Program To support tribes to more accurately and consistently report tribal crime data to the BIA and/or the FBI through technical assistance, training, and information sharing. Crimes known to some tribal law enforcement agencies published in Crime in the United States, 2009 and annually thereafter. Grants to Support Tribal Participation in Regional and National Databases To continue to include federally-recognized tribes as eligible entities for the National Instant Criminal Background Check System (NICS) Act Record Improvement Program and add federally- recognized tribes as eligible entities to the National Criminal History Improvement Program (NCHIP) grant awards. Tribes are eligible for awards as of FY 2009 (NICS) and FY 2011 (NCHIP). Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies To collect data from all state, local, and tribal law enforcement agencies on staffing, expenditures and functions. BJS will continue to implement strategies designed to accurately represent the work of tribal law enforcement agencies. Periodically since 1992. Latest report: 2004 census 2008 census report in 2011. Survey of Tribal Court Systems To gather administrative and operational information from tribal courts, prosecutors’ offices, and indigent defense providers. Award: August 2011. Design and Data Collection: 2011-2012. Analysis and Reporting: Early 2013. Survey of Jails in Indian Country The survey is an annual enumeration of jails, confinement facilities, detention centers, and other facilities operated by tribal authorities or the BIA. Data are collected intermittently via an addendum to the core survey on the physical conditions and operations of Indian country facilities. The addendum requests information on inmate medical services, mental health services, suicide prevention procedures, substance dependency programs, domestic violence counseling, sex offender treatment, education programs, and inmate work assignments. Annually since 1998. Latest report: 2009 survey 2010 survey report expected in 2011. Federal Justice Statistics Program To compile comprehensive information describing suspects and defendants processed in the federal criminal justice system. Ongoing since 1998. Annual data through 2009 available on the BJS website. BJS Native American Crime Information Website To provide users with easy-to-access and current information from existing and new data collection programs Design and populate website: 2010-2011. Public release: Late 2011. 14 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 attorney offices have jurisdiction for prosecuting felony cases occurring in Indian country under P.L. 280, and what types of crimes the office prosecuted. The findings from this data collection are in State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country on page 21. Federal Justice Statistics Program The Federal Justice Statistics Program (FJSP) provides comprehensive and detailed information about the federal justice system’s processing of criminal cases. The FJSP provides annual data on workload, activities, and outcomes associated with federal criminal cases. Information is acquired on all aspects of processing in the federal justice system, including arrests, prosecution decisions, referrals to magistrates, court dispositions, sentencing outcomes, sentence length, and time served. The FJSP receives the source data from the U.S. Marshals Service, Drug Enforcement Administration, Executive Office of U.S. Attorneys, Administrative Office of the U.S. Courts, U.S. Sentencing Commission, and the Federal Bureau of Prisons. BJS is currently developing research projects that will examine American Indian defendants who are processed in the federal justice system. Findings from the first of these projects, describing characteristics of American Indian youth who are processed in the federal criminal justice system, are in the Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System on page 35. References Crime in the United States, 2009, U.S. Department of Justice, Federal Bureau of Investigation, September 2010. Jails in Indian Country, 2009, NCJ 232223, BJS Web, February 2011. State Prosecutors Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007, NCJ 234241, BJS Web, June 2011. Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008. NCJ 234217, BJS Web, June 2011. Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System, NCJ 234218, BJS Web, June 2011. Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 15 Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 Brian A. Reaves, Ph.D., BJS Statistician In September 2008, American Indian tribes operated 178 law enforcement agencies that employed at least one full-time sworn officer with general arrest powers or the equivalent in part-time officers. The total includes 157 general purpose tribal police departments and 21 special jurisdiction agencies tasked with enforcing natural resources laws that pertain primarily to hunting and fishing on tribal lands. Collectively, tribes operated law enforcement agencies in 28 states. Washington (24), Arizona (22), Oklahoma (19), and New Mexico (17) had the largest numbers of tribal law enforcement agencies (figure 2.1). These findings are based on the 2008 Bureau of Justice Statistics’ (BJS) Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies. In addition to tribally operated agencies, the Department of the Interior’s (DOI) Bureau of Indian Affairs (BIA) operated 42 agencies that provided law enforcement Highlights � Tribally operated law enforcement agencies employed nearly 4,600 full-time personnel, including about 3,000 sworn officers. � The largest tribal law enforcement agency, the Navajo Police Department, employed 393 full-time sworn personnel in Arizona, New Mexico, and Utah. � Eleven of the 25 largest tribal law enforcement agencies served jurisdictions covering more than 1,000 square miles. � Overall, tribal police departments cost about $257 per resident to operate during FY 2008. � In addition to law enforcement functions, nearly all tribal police departments performed court-related functions, such as court security and serving process. � More than half of tribal police departments used community policing officers, and more than a third used school resource officers. � About 4 in 5 tribal police departments participated in one or more multiagency task forces. U.S. Department of Justice Office of Justice Programs Bureau of Justice Statistics June 2011 NCJ 234217 No tribally operated LE agencies Under 5 agencies 5-9 agencies 10 or more agencies Figure 2.1 Location of tribally operated law enforcement agencies, 2008 Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics, Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies, 2008 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201116 services in Indian country. Nationwide, BIA employed 277 full-time sworn personnel in 2008. Along with direct oversight of its own programs, BIA also provided technical assistance and some oversight to tribally operated agencies. On the more than 300 federal Indian reservation areas in the U.S., police officers may be tribal, federal, state, county, or municipal employees. Some areas may be served by more than one type of officer. Commonly, tribal police department funding, administration, and employees are based on the Indian Self-Determination and Education Assistance Act of 1975, (Public Law 93-638 or P.L. 638). This law allowed tribes to assume responsibility for many programs previously administered by the federal government, including law enforcement. P.L. 638 agencies operate with tribal employees under contract and with financial assistance from the BIA. Tribally operated agencies can also function under a self-governance compact with the BIA. This arrangement provides block grant payments, allowing for more tribal control than the line item funding of P.L. 638 contracts. Full tribal control over law enforcement services exists where such services are entirely funded by the tribal government. Jurisdiction over offenses in Indian country may lie with federal, state, or tribal agencies, depending on the offense, offender, victim, and offense location. Most tribes have cross- deputization agreements, often with neighboring nontribal agencies. These agreements allow law enforcement personnel from state, local, and tribal entities to cross jurisdictions in criminal cases, and can be used to enhance law enforcement capabilities in areas where state and tribal lands are contiguous and intermingled. In some instances, the number of agreements is large. For example, the Cherokee Nation Marshal Service is cross-deputized with 50 municipal, county, state, and federal agencies. Tribal police departments employed 2.3 full-time officers per 1,000 residents In September 2008, the 178 operating tribal law enforcement agencies employed more than 4,500 full- time personnel, including about 3,000 sworn officers (table 2.1). The 157 general purpose tribal police departments employed 4,294 full-time personnel, including 2,835 sworn officers and 1,459 civilian personnel. These agencies employed an additional 129 part-time personnel, including 80 sworn officers (not shown in table). The 21 natural resources agencies employed 271 full-time personnel, including 164 sworn officers and 107 civilian employees. These natural resources agencies also employed 11 part-time personnel, including 7 sworn officers (not shown in table). General purpose tribal police departments had a combined service population of about 1.2 million residents.* This corresponds to about 2.3 full-time sworn officers per 1,000 residents, which was the national average for all local police departments as of 2007. (See Local Police Departments, 2007, BJS Web, December 2010.) Collectively, tribal police departments cost $257 per resident to operate for 2008 (not shown in table). In 2007 the national average for all local police departments was $260 per resident. *Based on the American Indian service population counts published in BIA’s American Indian Population and Labor Force Report, 2005. The service population is the total number of enrolled tribal members and members from other tribes who live on or near the reservation and are eligible to use the BIA- funded tribal services. The service population excludes any non-Indian residents served by a tribally operated law enforcement agency and other persons using roads, stores, casinos, and other public places on tribal land. Table 2.1 Tribally operated law enforcement agencies, by type of agency and number of full-time sworn personnel, 2008 Type of agency and number of full-time sworn personnel Number of agencies Number of full-time employees Total Sworn Civilian All agencies 178 4,565 2,999 1,566 General purpose police departments Total 157 4,294 2,835 1,459 50 or more 6 1,397 871 526 25-49 19 955 607 348 10-24 61 1,380 955 425 5-9 47 479 332 147 Under 5 24 83 70 13 Natural resources agencies Total 21 271 164 107 10-24 8 154 107 47 5-9 4 38 29 9 Under 5 9 79 28 51 Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 17 11 of the 25 largest tribal law enforcement agencies served jurisdictions of more than 1,000 square miles The 25 largest tribally operated agencies employed at least 25 full- time sworn personnel. The largest agency, the Navajo Police Department, employed 393 full-time officers to serve tribal lands in Arizona, New Mexico, and Utah (table 2.2). The next largest were the Seminole Police Department (Florida) with 144 officers, and the Salt River Police Department (Arizona) with 125 officers. The BIA service population for the 25 largest agencies ranged from less than 1,000 to about 200,000 residents. Although not all reservations are open to the public, many tribal law enforcement agencies deal with a significant number of daily visitors in addition to the resident population. The natural resources of tribal lands attract visitors, as do conference facilities and casinos. All of the 25 largest agencies had at least one casino operating within their jurisdictional area. The amount of land area served by a tribal law enforcement agency can be quite large. For example, the Navajo Police Department has jurisdiction over about 22,000 square miles, a larger land area than any county in the continental United States. Ten other agencies among the 25 largest had jurisdictional areas exceeding 1,000 square miles, a larger land area than any city in the continental United States. Table 2.2 The 25 largest tribally operated law enforcement agencies, by the number of full-time sworn personnel, 2008 Name and location of agency Number of full-time sworn personnel BIA service population, 2005 Full-time sworn personnel per 1,000 residents Reservation land area (square miles) Full-time sworn personnel per 25 square miles Navajo Police Department (AZ, NM, UT) 393 192,067 2.0 22,174 0.4 Seminole Police Department (FL) 144 3,165 45.5 141 25.5 Salt River Police Department (AZ) 125 7,313 17.1 81 38.6 Gila River Indian Community Police Department (AZ) 93 14,966 6.2 584 4.0 Tohono O’odham Police Department (AZ) 66 26,673 2.5 4,453 0.4 Choctaw Police Department (MS) 50 8,313 6.0 25 50.0 Oglala Sioux Tribe Department of Public Safety (SD) 49 43,146 1.1 3,159 0.4 Cherokee Indian Police Department (NC) 45 13,562 3.3 83 13.6 Muscogee (Creek) Nation Lighthorse Tribal Police (OK) 39 55,817 0.7 4,648 0.2 Miccosukee Police Department (FL) 36 589 61.1 128 7.0 Poarch Creek Tribal Police Department (AL) 33 1,567 21.1 0.4 -- Cherokee Nation Marshal Service (OK) 32 197,684 0.2 6,702 0.1 Choctaw Nation Tribal Police Department (OK) 32 99,371 0.3 10,613 0.1 Colville Tribal Police Department (WA) 32 5,052 6.3 2,117 0.4 Saginaw Chippewa Tribal Police Department (MI) 30 1,799 16.7 218 3.4 Tulalip Tribal Police Services (WA) 30 2,869 10.5 35 21.4 Warm Springs Tribal Police Department (OR) 30 4,079 7.4 1,011 0.7 White Mountain Apache Police Department (AZ) 30 12,213 2.5 2,628 0.3 Isleta Police Department (NM) 29 3,980 7.3 331 2.2 Yakama Nation Tribal Police Department (WA) 28 16,815 1.7 2,153 0.3 Pascua Yaqui Tribal Police Department (AZ) 27 14,787 1.8 2 -- Puyallup Tribal Police Department (WA) 27 24,016 1.1 29 23.3 Rosebud Sioux Tribal Police Department (SD) 27 22,293 1.2 1,388 0.5 Red Lake Tribal Police Department (MN) 26 10,338 2.5 880 0.7 Oneida Indian Nation Police (NY) 25 650 38.5 0.1 -- Note: Land area data are from the U.S. Census Bureau, and include reservation land only. --Reservation land area is less than 25 square miles. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201118 Tribal law enforcement agencies were responsible for a broad range of services and functions during 2008 Nearly all general purpose tribal police departments were responsible for traditional law enforcement functions, such as routine patrol (100%), responding to citizen requests for service (100%), special events and crowd control (98%), criminal investigation (96%), and traffic enforcement (96%) (figure 2.2). About 4 in 5 departments were responsible for parking enforcement (80%), and about 2 in 3 departments dispatched calls for service (66%). About 3 in 5 general purpose tribal police departments had full-time community policing officers A majority of tribal police departments used a community policing approach in their efforts to prevent crime and maintain partnerships with the communities they serve. About three-fifths (59%) of departments had full-time sworn personnel serving as community policing officers (table 2.3). As of September 2008, about 500 tribal police officers were designated as community policing officers. In 2000, 73% of tribal agencies reported using community policing officers, with about 700 designated as such. For more than a third (36%) of tribal police departments, community policing efforts extended into the schools, with 82 full-time sworn personnel assigned as school resource officers. Although the percentage of departments using school resource officers in 2008 was about the same as in 2000 (37%), the total number of officers was about half of 2000 levels. Nearly all tribal police departments performed a variety of court-related functions In addition to law enforcement duties, nearly all tribal police departments were responsible for a variety of court-related functions (figure 2.3). The most common functions were executing arrest warrants (95%), enforcing protection orders (92%), serving process (89%), apprehending fugitives (88%), and providing court security (75%). Table 2.3 Use of community policing and school resource officers by tribal police departments, 2000 and 2008 2000 2008 Community policing officers Percent of agencies using 73% 59% Number of officers 714 503 School resource officers Percent of agencies using 37% 36% Number of officers 162 82 0 20 40 60 80 100 Percent of agencies Dispatching calls Parking enforcement Accident investigation Crime investigation Tra�c law enforcement Special events/crowd control Responding to calls for service Routine patrol Type of function Figure 2.2 Selected law enforcement functions performed by tribal police departments, 2008 Figure 2.3 Selected court-related functions performed by tribal police departments, 2008 0 20 40 60 80 100 Percent of agencies Type of function Enforcing child support orders Serving eviction notices Inmate transport Court security Apprehension of fugitives Serving process Enforcing protection orders Executing arrest warrants Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 19 Nearly half of tribal police departments were responsible for search and rescue operations Nearly 9 in 10 tribal police departments performed one or more special public safety functions, the most common being emergency management (65%) and animal control (64%) (figure 2.4). About a third (31%) provided emergency medical services. Nearly a fifth provided fire services (19%) and school crossing services (18%). More than half (58%) of tribal police departments performed at least one specialized function, such as search and rescue (43%), tactical operations (26%), or underwater recovery (10%). About 1 in 6 agencies operated at least one jail (17%), and about 1 in 10 agencies operated an overnight lockup facility separate from a jail (10%). (For more information, see Jails in Indian County, 2009, BJS Web, February 2011.) The 21 special jurisdiction agencies, whose primary focus was the enforcement of natural resources laws, performed a variety of functions as well. In addition to providing patrol and response services, a majority of these agencies performed the following functions: criminal investigation (82%), search and rescue (71%), apprehension of fugitives (59%), animal control (59%), traffic enforcement (59%), and dispatching calls for service (53%) (not shown in figure). About two-thirds of general purpose tribal police departments participated in a multiagency drug task force About 4 in 5 (78%) tribal police departments partnered with federal, state, and local agencies in multiagency task forces to combat crime problems in Indian country during 2008. These task forces allow participating agencies to share in pooled resources, information, and expertise across jurisdictional boundaries. Tribal police departments were most likely to participate in task forces formed to combat drug trafficking (66% of agencies) (figure 2.5). About 2 in 5 (41%) departments participated in multiagency gang task forces, and about a third (32%) participated in violent crime task forces. Smaller percentages of tribal police departments participated in anti- terrorism (17%) or human trafficking (9%) task forces. 0 20 40 60 80 Percent of agencies Jail operation School crossing services Fire services Tactical operations (SWAT) Emergency medical services Search and rescue Animal control Emergency management Type of function Figure 2.4 Selected special functions performed by tribal police departments, 2008 0 20 40 60 80 Percent of agencies Human tra�cking Anti- terrorism Violent crime GangsDrug tra�cking One or more types Type of function Figure 2.5 Task force participation of tribal police departments, 2008 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201120 Methodology The Bureau of Justice Statistics’ (BJS) Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies (CSLLEA) is conducted every 4 years to provide a complete enumeration of agencies and their employees. Employment data are reported for sworn and nonsworn personnel and, within these categories, by full-time or part- time status. Agencies also complete a checklist of functions they regularly perform, or for which they have primary responsibility. The CSLLEA provides national data on the number of state and local law enforcement agencies and employees for general purpose local police departments (including tribal agencies), sheriffs’ offices, the primary state law enforcement agencies, and special jurisdiction (e.g., natural resources) agencies. It also serves as the sampling frame for BJS surveys of law enforcement agencies. The 2008 CSLLEA form was mailed to approximately 20,000 agencies that were determined to potentially be operating on the reference date of September 30, 2008. This master list was created by compiling information from the following sources: � the 2004 CSLLEA � lists provided by Peace Officer Standards and Training offices, and other state agencies � an FBI list of agencies requesting new identifiers since the 2004 CSLLEA. Responding agencies were screened for eligibility and were excluded if any of the following conditions existed on the CSLLEA reference date of September 30, 2008: � The agency employed only part-time officers, and the total combined hours worked for these officers averaged less than 35 hours per week. � The agency contracted or outsourced to another agency for performance of all services. � The agency was closed, a duplicate listing, or otherwise an invalid entry on the master list. � The agency did not employ personnel with general arrest powers. � The agency did not operate with funds from a state, local, special district, or tribal government. � All sworn officers volunteered their time on an unpaid basis. Data on number and type of personnel were obtained from all eligible tribal agencies. For general purpose tribal police departments, the item response rates were as follows: community policing and school resource officers, 100%; agency functions, 99%; task force participation, 99%; and operating budget, 87%. References American Indians and Crime, NCJ 173386, BJS Web, February 1999. American Indian Population and Labor Force Report, 2005, U.S. Department of the Interior, Bureau of Indian Affairs, Office of Indian Services. Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies, 2008, NCJ 233982, BJS Web, June 2011. Census of Tribal Justice Agencies in Indian Country, 2002, NCJ 205332, BJS Web, December 2005. Indian Country Law Enforcement Review, U.S. Department of Justice, December 1999. Jails in Indian Country, 2009, NCJ 232223, BJS Web, February 2011. Local Police Departments, 2007, NCJ 231174, BJS Web, December 2010. Policing on American Indian Reservations, U.S. Department of Justice, National Institute of Justice, NCJ 186185, September 2001. Tribal Law Enforcement, 2000, NCJ 197936, BJS Web, January 2003. State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 21 State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 Steven W. Perry, Ron Malega, Ph.D., and Duren Banks, Ph.D., BJS Statisticians In 2007, 93 state court prosecutors’ offices reported jurisdiction under Public Law 83-280 (P.L. 280) for felonies committed in Indian country. Seventy-three percent of these offices prosecuted at least one felony case that arose from Indian country in 2007, including at least one offense that involved drugs (63%), domestic violence (60%), or aggravated assault (58%). This report presents selected findings from the Bureau of Justice Statistics’s (BJS) 2007 National Census of State Prosecutors. Criminal jurisdiction in Indian country is divided among federal, state, and tribal governments. Jurisdiction in a specific incident depends on the nature of the offense, whether the offender or victim was a tribal member, and the state in which the crime occurred. Crimes committed in Indian country are often subject to concurrent jurisdiction between multiple criminal justice agencies. The Major Crimes Act (18 U.S.C. § 1153), as amended, grants concurrent federal jurisdiction for 16 major crimes committed by Native Americans occurring in Indian country. State jurisdiction for crimes committed in Indian country is primarily provided for under P.L. 280. Tribal courts maintain concurrent jurisdiction when federal or state jurisdiction is applied. State prosecutors’ offices generally do not have jurisdiction over crimes committed in Indian country due to the sovereign status of federally recognized tribes in the United States. However, state prosecutors’ offices in 16 states may exercise jurisdiction over crimes committed on tribal lands under P.L. 280. This law established state jurisdiction over offenses committed by or against American Indians in Indian country, including federally recognized reservations, tribal communities, and identified trust lands. P.L. 280 is mandatory for 6 states and optional for 10 states. Highlights � Ninety-three state court prosecutors’ offices in the 16 P.L. 280 states reported jurisdiction for felonies committed in Indian country under P.L. 280. � Seventy-three percent of offices with jurisdiction in Indian country reported prosecuting at least one felony case committed in Indian country. � Most offices in P.L. 280 states prosecuted at least one offense involving drugs (63%), domestic violence (60%), or aggravated assault (58%). � Eighteen offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states with jurisdiction for Indian country prosecuted at least one rape, and 12 offices prosecuted a homicide. � Of state prosecutors’ offices that reported jurisdiction for felony cases in Indian country under P.L. 280, 70% served judicial districts with populations of less than 100,000 residents. � Offices with jurisdiction for felony crimes committed in Indian country had an average operating budget of $5.2 million in 2007. Criminal jurisdic tion in I ndian countr y Tribal jurisdiction � Crimes committed by Native Americans in Indian country. Sentences are limited to a maximum 3-year sentence of incarceration per count and 9 years per case (124 U.S.C. 2258 § 234 (a) (b)). Federal jurisdiction � Pursuant to the Major Crimes Act of 1885. 18 U.S.C. § 1153 and subsequent amendments State jurisdiction � All crimes on tribal lands specified under Public Law 83-280. 18 U.S.C. § 1162 � Crimes committed on tribal lands in which neither the victim nor the offender is a tribal member. Note: Criminal jurisdiction in Indian country depends on several factors, including the identity of the defendant, victim, type of offense, and where the crime was committed. U.S. Department of Justice Office of Justice Programs Bureau of Justice Statistics June 2011, NCJ 234241 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201122 According to the 2002 Census of Tribal Justice Agencies, 94 of the 123 responding tribes in mandatory P.L. 280 states relied on state courts. The 2002 Census was limited to American Indian tribes in the lower 48 states, so tribes in Alaska were excluded. The Census also found that 19 of 90 reporting tribes in optional P.L. 280 states relied on state courts (table 3.1). The federal government retains criminal jurisdiction for major crimes committed in Indian country in the remaining states where P.L. 280 does not apply. States retain jurisdiction for non-Indian crimes (those in which neither the offender nor the victim is a tribal member) committed in Indian country.* In 2007, 1,548 state court prosecutors’ offices were in states not affected by P.L. 280 and were excluded from this report. The 93 state prosecutors’ offices reporting jurisdiction under P.L. 280 in mandatory and optional states represent 14% of all state prosecutors’ offices in states affected by P.L. 280. Nearly all of these served districts that overlapped with or were adjacent to tribal lands (figure 3.1). Approximately a fifth of state prosecutors in mandatory P.L. 280 states reported jurisdiction for crimes committed in Indian country P.L. 280 gave select states legal jurisdiction over tribal members to prosecute crimes occurring on the reservation under existing state laws. These mandatory P.L. 280 states include California, Minnesota (except the Red Lake Reservation), Nebraska, Oregon (except the Warm Springs Reservation), Wisconsin, and Alaska (table 3.2). *Some tribes have been affected by states that have received a federal mandate to exercise jurisdiction outside of P.L. 280, e.g., through state-wide enactments, restoration acts, or land claims settlement acts (Tribal Court Clearinghouse, 2010, www.tribal-institute.org/ lists/jurisdiction.htm). Table 3.1 Number of tribes participating in the Census of Tribal Justice Agencies in Indian Country, by P.L. 280 status, type of court systems, and state, 2002 Number of tribes using— Participating in census Tribal justice systems Indigenous courts CFR courtsa Tribal courts Relying on state courtsb Mandatory states 123 39 8 9 37 94 California 88 7 2 7 7 74 Minnesota 12 12 3 0 12 4 Nebraska 4 3 0 2 3 2 Oregon 8 8 1 0 8 6 Wisconsin 11 9 2 0 7 8 Optional states 90 80 13 11 74 19 Arizona 17 16 3 0 16 0 Florida 1 0 0 0 0 1 Idaho 4 4 1 0 4 1 Iowa 1 0 0 0 0 1 Montana 6 6 1 0 5 0 Nevada 16 14 1 4 13 6 North Dakota 3 3 0 0 3 0 South Dakota 9 9 0 2 9 0 Utah 4 2 0 2 2 2 Washington 29 26 7 3 22 8 Note: The 2002 Census of Tribal Justice Agencies was limited to American Indian tribes in the lower 48 states. Source: Table reproduced from Census of Tribal Justice Agencies in Indian Country, 2002, NCJ 205332, BJS Web, December 2005. aCourt of Federal Regulations (CFR) operated by the Bureau of Indian Affairs (BIA). bTribes that rely on state court for jusidical services (e.g., felony courts, court-ordered treatment, and child support enforcement). Table 3.2 State prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction for crimes committed in Indian country, by P.L. 280 status and state, 2007 Number of offices— All prosecutors’ offices in P.L. 280 states* With jurisdiction for felony cases occurring in Indian country under P.L. 280 Prosecuting at least one felony case All P.L. 280 states 672 93 68 Mandatory states 294 56 47 Alaska 1 1 -- California 48 23 21 Minnesota 76 15 15 Nebraska 81 3 1 Oregon 31 7 4 Wisconsin 57 7 6 Optional states 378 37 21 Arizona 11 1 1 Florida 16 1 1 Idaho 34 6 4 Iowa 93 1 1 Montana 46 5 1 Nevada 15 2 0 North Dakota 43 2 1 South Dakota 58 1 1 Utah 26 3 2 Washington 36 15 9 Note: The 2007 Census of State Court Prosecutors included 2,330 offices, 66% (1,548) of which were located in states not affected by P.L. 280, and therefore were excluded from all analyses. --No information reported. *Excludes data missing for 110 offices. 23 M an da to ry P .L . 2 80 st at es Op tio na l P .L . 2 80 st at es In di an re se rv at io n (U .S . C en su s B ur ea u) Pr os ec ut or s’ o� ce s r ep or tin g ju ris di ct io n in In di an Co un try u nd er P .L . 2 80 Fi g u r e 3 .1 St at e p ro se cu to rs ’ o ffi ce s re p o rt in g ju ri sd ic ti o n in In d ia n c o u n tr y u n d er P .L . 2 80 , 2 00 7 N ot e: P ro se cu to rs ’ o ffi ce s i n no n- P.L . 2 80 st at es a re n ot sh ow n. So ur ce : B ur ea u of Ju st ic e St at ist ic s Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201124 In 2007, 19% of all state prosecutors’ offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states reported jurisdiction for felony cases occurring in Indian country. P.L. 280 permitted other states to acquire either complete or partial jurisdiction over crimes committed in Indian country at their option: Arizona, Florida, Idaho, Iowa, Montana, Nevada, North Dakota, South Dakota, Utah, and Washington. Ten percent of all prosecutors’ offices in optional P.L. 280 states reported jurisdiction for felony cases in Indian country in 2007. About three-quarters of offices with P.L. 280 jurisdiction prosecuted a felony case from Indian country in 2007 Sixty-eight of the 93 prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction in Indian country reported prosecuting at least one felony case committed in Indian country in 2007. Forty-seven offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states reported prosecuting at least one offense committed in Indian country, and 21 offices in optional P.L. 280 states reported prosecuting at least one offense committed in Indian country in 2007. Most offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states with jurisdiction for felony offenses in Indian country also reported prosecuting at least one drug-related crime (42 of 56 offices), domestic violence offense (40), aggravated assault (38), parole or probation violation (31), or a crime involving sexual assault or sexual abuse (30) (figure 3.2). Offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states with jurisdiction for Indian country also reported prosecuting serious felony offenses, including 18 offices that prosecuted at least one rape committed in Indian country and 12 offices that prosecuted a homicide. Prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction in Indian country had an average of 16 assistant prosecutors on staff The 2007 National Census of State Prosecutors collected operational and administrative information from state prosecutors’ offices, including budgets, staffing, and caseload. Offices reporting jurisdiction for crimes committed under P.L. 280 were not asked to disaggregate office resources or operations by whether they were directed toward crimes committed in Indian country or elsewhere in the judicial district. The census asked respondents to provide or estimate the total number of felony cases closed in 2007. The survey did not ask respondents to provide information on the number of cases that arose from crimes committed in Indian country. This section describes the entire operations of the state prosecutors’ offices reporting jurisdiction under P.L. 280, not operations specific to crimes committed in Indian country. Homicide Rape Robbery Sexual assault/abuse Parole/probation violation Aggravated assault Domestic violence Drug-related All felony cases prosecuted in Indian Country, under P.L. 280 Optional P.L. 280 Mandatory P.L. 280 Number of o�ces 47 21 42 17 40 16 38 16 31 15 30 10 21 8 18 5 12 4 Figure 3.2 State prosecutors’ offices reporting prosecution of specific crimes in Indian country, by P.L. 280 status, 2007 State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 25 Most (71) state prosecutors’ offices that reported jurisdiction for felony cases occurring in Indian country under P.L. 280 served judicial districts with populations of less than 100,000 residents or were part-time offices. In mandatory P.L. 280 states, 7 of the 56 offices with jurisdiction in Indian country served districts with 250,000 or more residents (table 3.3). Offices with jurisdiction for felony crimes committed in Indian country had an average 2007 budget of $5.2 million, or an expenditure of about $31 per district resident. The median budget was $722,000. The office staff included an average of 16 assistant prosecutors, 3 victim advocates, 4 legal services staff, and 19 support staff (table 3.4). Offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states reported an average of 61 total staff, including 19 assistant prosecutors, 8 investigators, and 22 support staff. Offices in optional P.L. 280 states reported an average of 38 total staff, 11 assistant prosecutors, 1 investigator, and 14 support staff. Offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states, reported closing a similar number of felony cases in 2007 compared to optional state offices. State prosecutors’ offices in optional P.L. 280 states closed 1,784 felony cases in 2007, while offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states closed 1,699 felony cases. Table 3.3 Type of state prosecutors’ offices reporting jurisdiction in Indian country, by P.L. 280 status, 2007 Total P.L. 280 Status Population served Mandatory Optional All offices 93 56 37 Full-time offices serving a judicial district with— 1 million or more residents 4 2 2 250,000 to 999,999 5 5 0 100,000 to 249,999 13 8 5 99,999 or fewer 65 37 28 Part-time offices* 6 4 2 *Part-time offices are defined as those that reported a part-time chief prosecutor in 2007. Table 3.4 Budget, staffing, and caseload of state prosecutors’ offices, by P.L. 280 status, 2007 Total P.L. 280 status Mandatory Optional Mean Median Mean Median Mean Median Total resident population served 156,495 28,893 177,407 28,965 124,846 28,606 Total operating budget $5,173,831 $722,208 $6,560,838 $735,735 $3,074,577 $670,000 Budget per resident population served $31 $26 $35 $27 $25 $24 Total staffa 51 12 61 12 38 12 Chief prosecutor 1 1 1 1 1 1 Assistant prosecutors 16 3 19 4 11 3 Civil prosecutors 2 0 1 0 4 1 Supervisors 2 1 2 0 2 1 Managers 1 0 1 0 0 0 Victim advocates 3 1 3 1 2 1 Legal services 4 0 3 0 4 1 Investigators 5 0 8 0 1 0 Support staff 19 3 22 4 14 3 Felony cases closedb 1,733 300 1,699 300 1,784 275 Note: Statistics include imputed data for some offices. Data were missing for 3 offices that did not provide total operating budget, 1 office that did not provide staffing information, and 6 offices that did not provide the number of felony cases closed. See Methodology for more information. aAll staff statistics are presented as full-time equivalent staff, calculated as the number of full-time staff plus 50% of the number of half time staff. bIncludes all cases charged as a felony that had a judgment of conviction, acquittal, or dismissal, with or without prejudice, entered by the court. Cases closed include all felony cases closed by the prosecutors’ offices and include an unknown number of cases committed in Indian country. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201126 Methodology The 2007 National Census of State Court Prosecutors (NCSP-07) surveyed 2,330 chief prosecutors in the United States who handled felony cases in state courts of general jurisdiction. The census did not include municipal attorneys or county attorneys who primarily operate in courts of limited jurisdiction. This report describes characteristics of offices that reported jurisdiction for crimes committed in Indian country under P.L. 280 in 2007. Most (66%) state court prosecutors’ offices included in the 2007 census were in states not affected by P.L. 280 and are excluded from this report. The operational and administrative characteristics described in this report represent the functions of the entire office and are not restricted to those functions, staff, budget, or other resources specifically devoted to crimes committed in Indian country, unless otherwise noted. Data Imputations BJS relied on previously reported data and valid office characteristics to impute values for critical variables where missing. These critical variables, found in Table 3.4, include the total operating budget, total staff, full- or part-time status of chief prosecutor, number of assistant prosecutors, and number of felony cases closed. Critical variables that were missing in 2007 were imputed from the same office’s response to the 2001 Census of State Prosecutors wherever possible. For each jurisdiction with valid 2001 and 2007 data, an adjustment ratio was calculated as the ratio of the critical variable’s 2001 value to its 2007 value. All ratios greater than the 90th percentile were discarded for imputation purposes. For those offices missing 2007 data, a hot deck imputation procedure was employed to impute the adjustment ratio value from the office’s nearest neighbor in terms of state and population size. Where there were no suitable donors in the same state, a donor of similar population size was used. The 2001 data were then adjusted using the imputed adjustment ratio to create the imputed 2007 value for the critical variable where missing. This procedure was followed for 3 offices missing total operating budget, 1 office missing staffing information, and 6 offices missing the number of felony cases closed. Reference Census of Tribal Justice Agencies in Indian Country, 2002, NCJ 205332, BJS Web, `December 2005. Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 27 Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 Todd D. Minton, BJS Statistician At midyear 2009, a total of 2,176 inmates were confined in Indian country jails, a 1.9% increase from the 2,135 inmates confined at midyear 2008 (figure 4.1). This count was based on data from 80 facilities, including jails, confinement facilities, detention centers, and other correctional facilities, that were in operation in Indian country at midyear 2009. For 2008, the number of inmates was based on data for 82 facilities in operation at midyear 2008. The number of inmates held in Indian country jails between 2004 and 2009 increased by 25% from 1,745 inmates to 2,176. The number of jails in Indian country has increased between 2004 and 2009 The Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS) collected data from 68 correctional facilities in Indian country in 2004, from 79 in 2007, 82 in 2008, and 80 in 2009. The survey was not conducted in 2005 and 2006. Over the 5-year period, a number of facilities closed and new facilities became operational. Eleven facilities permanently closed between 2004 and 2009, and a total of 21 facilities were newly Highlights � The number of inmates confined in Indian country jails increased by 1.9% between midyear 2008 and 2009, reaching 2,176 inmates. � Between June 2008 and June 2009, the average daily jail population in Indian country increased by 12%, and the percentage of occupied bed space increased from 64.2% to 73.5%. � Eleven jails (14% of all facilities) held 51% of inmates confined at midyear 2009. � During June 2009, the number of inmates admitted to Indian country jails (11,357) was about 5 times the size of the average daily population (2,124). � The expected average length of stay increased by a half day from 5.1 days during June 2008 to 5.6 days during June 2009. � Indian country jail authorities reported no deaths in custody between July 1, 2008, and June 30, 2009, down from 4 reported deaths during the 12-month period ending June 30, 2008. � Attempted suicides by inmates declined from 78 in 2008 to 56 in 2009. � Indian country jails held fewer inmates for domestic violence at midyear 2009 (252), continuing the downward trend in the number held for this offense since 2007 (362). � The percentage of certified correctional officers working in Indian country jails increased steadily, from 63% at midyear 2007 to 79% at midyear 2009. U.S. Department of Justice Office of Justice Programs Bureau of Justice Statistics June 2011, NCJ 232223 0 400 800 1,200 1,600 2,000 2,400 Number of inmates 20092008200720042003200220012000 At midyear Figure 4.1 Inmates confined in Indian country jails, midyear 2000-2004 and 2007-2009 Note: The Survey of Jails in Indian Country was not conducted in 2005 and 2006. Midyear count is the number of inmates held on the last weekday in June. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201128 constructed. BJS estimated inmate population counts for 7 facilities in 2004 and 4 facilities in 2007 that did not respond to the surveys. All known operating facilities responded to the 2008 and 2009 surveys. (See Methodology for additional details on facility counts and participation in the surveys.) (See Methodology in Jails in Indian Country, 2009, NCJ 232223, BJS Web, February 2010, for additional details on facility counts and participation in the surveys.) On an average day in June, the percentage of occupied bed space increased from 64.2% to 73.5% At midyear 2009, the 80 jail facilities in Indian country were rated to hold 2,891 inmates, down from 2,963 in 82 facilities during the same period in 2008 (table 4.1). The average daily population (ADP) in June—the population measure used to calculate percent of capacity occupied—increased by nearly 12%, from 1,903 inmates (June 2008) to 2,124 (June 2009), while the capacity to hold inmates decreased by 2%. Consequently, the percentage of rated capacity occupied in Indian country jails increased from 64% to 73% during the period. On June 30, 2009, the 80 facilities held a total of 2,176 inmates and were operating at 75% of rated capacity, remaining relatively stable since 2007. From June 2004 to June 2009, the overall number of beds (or rated capacity) grew at a faster rate (34%) than the the inmate population (25%). Small number of jails held more than half of the inmate population Eleven jails held more than half (51%) of the total inmate population at midyear 2009 (table 4.2). Between midyear 2008 and midyear 2009, the population in these jails increased by 247 inmates (29%). In 2008, 9 of the 11 facilities held the majority of jail inmates in Indian country. Over the 365-day period, 6 jails that held the majority of inmates in Indian country in 2008 experienced large declines in their jail populations. The combined decrease in the size of the jail population in these facilities was 33% (90 inmates) from midyear 2008 to midyear 2009. Among the 11 facilities holding the majority of inmates in 2009, the Gila River Department of Rehabilitation and Supervision - Adult facility reported the largest decline (30 inmates or 17%) in the number of jail inmates. The jail population in this facility has decreased by 92 inmates (38%) from its peak of 241 inmates reported at midyear 2007. Table 4.1 Inmates, rated capacity, and percent of capacity occupied in Indian country jails, 2004 and 2007–2009 2004 2007 2008 2009 Number of inmates Midyeara 1,745 2,163 2,135 2,176 ADPb 1,622 2,046 1,903 2,124 Rated capacity 2,162 2,900 2,963 2,891 Percent of capacity occupiedc Midyear 80.7% 74.6% 72.1% 75.3% ADP 75.0 70.6 64.2 73.5 Number of operating facilities 68 79 82 80 aMidyear count is the number of inmates held on the last weekday in June. bAverage daily population (ADP) is the sum of the number of inmates held on each day in June, divided by 30. cPopulation as a percent of capacity occupied is calculated by dividing the population count of a facility by its rated capacity and multiplying by 100. Table 4.2 Jails in Indian country that held the majority of inmates in 2009 compared to 2008, by facility Custody population at midyear* Change in population Facility 2008 2009 Number Percent Total, 11 facilities 859 1,106 247 29% Tohono O’odham Adult Detention Center (AZ) 137 192 55 40% Gila River Department of Rehabilitation and Supervision - Adult (AZ) 179 149 -30 -17 San Carlos Department of Corrections and Rehabilitation - Adult and Juvenile Detention (AZ) 88 147 59 67 Truxton Canyon Adult Detention Center (AZ) 39 105 66 169 White Mountain Apache Detention Center (AZ) 101 95 -6 -6 Oglala Sioux Tribal Offenders Facility (SD) 52 95 43 83 Standing Rock Law Enforcement and Adult Detention Center (ND) 71 93 22 31 Nisqually Adult Corrections (WA) 59 73 14 24 Menominee Tribal Detention Facility (WI) 54 53 -1 -2 Navajo Department of Corrections - Shiprock Police Department and Adult Detention (NM) 46 52 6 13 Laguna Tribal Police and Detention Center (NM) 33 52 19 58 Note: Based on facilities that held the most inmates on June 30, 2009. *Midyear count is the number of inmates held on the last weekday in June. Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 29 Two facilities, the Truxton Canyon Adult Detention Center and the Laguna Tribal Police and Detention Center, were among the 11 facilities holding the majority of jail inmates in 2009. These 2 facilities were not among the 11 facilities holding the majority of inmates in 2008. (See Jails in Indian Country, 2008, BJS Web, December 2008.) The Truxton Canyon Adult Detention Center reported the largest increase in the inmate population (66 inmates or 169%) between midyear 2008 and midyear 2009. The Laguna Tribal Police and Detention Center increased by 58% (19 inmates) between 2008 and 2009. Based on the 80 facilities responding to the survey in both 2008 and 2009, the overall change in the inmate population (up 45 inmates) was relatively small. Thirty-three facilities, which were mostly the larger facilities, accounted for this increase (not shown in table). Change in the size of the jail population in Indian country was varied. More than half of the 80 jails experienced either a decline (40 jails) or no change (7 jails) in the size of their inmate population over the 12-month period ending midyear 2009. Overall, the 50% increase (415 inmates) in the jail population in 33 jails was offset by a 30% decline (370 inmates) in 40 jails. The use of jail space varied by facility size Indian country jails rated to hold 25 to 49 inmates were operating at 89% of their rated capacity on June 30, 2009, and at 79% on an average day in June. An average day in June was based on the ADP, or the sum of the numbers held on each day in June divided by 30. In contrast, the lowest percentage of capacity occupied during June 2009 was among the 11 small jails rated to hold fewer than 10 inmates. These facilities were operating at 21% of rated capacity at midyear and at 17% of capacity on an average day in June 2009 (figure 4.2). Compared to facilities in all other size categories, the large jails with a rated capacity of 50 or more inmates reported the only increase in occupied bed space between 2008 and 2009. The percentage of capacity occupied in these jails increased from 51% to 69% during the 12 months ending at midyear 2009, and from 49% to 73% on an average day in June 2008 and 2009. The amount of bed space occupied was also measured based on a facility’s most crowded day in June. Nearly half (38 facilities) of the 80 facilities in Indian country were operating above rated capacity on the most crowded day in June (table 4.3). Of those Table 4.3 Number of Indian country jails, by percent of rated capacity occupied, June 2009 Number of jails Percent of capacity occupieda Midyearb ADPc Peakd Less than 25% 17 20 7 25-49% 15 11 8 50-74% 19 21 15 75-100% 11 15 12 More than 100% 18 13 38 aPopulation as a percent of capacity occupied is calculated by dividing the population count of a facility by its rated capacity and multiplying by 100. bMidyear count is the number of inmates held on the last weekday in June. cAverage daily population (ADP) is the sum of the number of inmates held on each day in June, divided by 30. dPeak population is the population held on the day in June in which the custody population of a facility was the largest. 0 20 40 60 80 100 120 140 Peak 50 or more25 to 4910 to 24Fewer than 10 inmatesTotal Percent of capacity occupied ADP Midyear Figure 4.2 Rated capacity occupied, by type of inmate count, June 2009 Note: Rated capacity is the maximum number of beds or inmates assigned by a rating official. Midyear count is the number of inmates held on the last weekday in June. Average daily population (ADP) is the sum of the number of inmates held on each day in June divided by 30. Peak population is the population held on the day in June in which the custody population of a facility was the largest. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201130 facilities, 18 were operating above rated capacity on June 30, and 13 were operating above rated capacity on an average day during June 2009. High volumes of admissions of inmates were processed through Indian country jails Eighty Indian country jails admitted 11,357 persons during June 2009, up slightly from 11,149 admissions in 81 facilities during June 2008 (table 4.4). The number of admissions grew by 1.6% in the 79 facilities that reported data on admissions in both June 2009 (11,323) and June 2008 (11,147) (not shown in table). Admissions to facilities rated to hold between 25 to 49 inmates accounted for about 48% (5,503) of all admissions in June 2009, down from 59% of all admissions in June 2008. The largest Indian country jails accounted for less than 20% of all facilities and reported a total increase of nearly 75% in the number of jail admissions during the 12-month period. Admissions to the largest Indian country jails increased from 1,915 inmates to 3,342 from June 2008 to June 2009. The 15 jails rated to hold 50 or more inmates had the highest average number of admissions per month (233), compared to jails in all other size categories (not shown in table). Inmate deaths and attempted suicides in Indian country jails declined Indian country jail authorities reported no deaths in custody between July 1, 2008, and June 30, 2009, down from 4 reported deaths during the 12-month period ending June 30, 2008. Attempted suicides by inmates declined from 78 in 2008 to 56 in 2009. Expected length of stay was 5.6 days for Indian country jail inmates in June 2009 During June 2009, the expected average length of stay for inmates confined in Indian country jails was 5.6 days, up from 5.1 days during June 2008. Length of stay is the time held in custody from admission to release. The expected length of stay for inmates was the highest (9.1 days) Table 4.4 Admissions and expected length of stay in Indian country jails during June, by facility size, June 2009 Facility sizea Number of facilities ADPb Estimated June admissions Expected average length of stayc Total 80 2,124 11,357 5.6 days Fewer than 10 inmates 11 9 133 2.1 10 to 24 24 276 2,379 3.5 25 to 49 30 820 5,503 4.5 50 or more 15 1,018 3,342 9.1 Note: Detail may not sum to total due to rounding. aBased on the rated capacity, the maximum number of beds or inmates assigned by a rating official. bAverage daily population (ADP) is the sum of the number of inmates held on each day in June, divided by 30. cExpected length of stay was calculated by dividing the average daily population (ADP) by the number of June admissions, and multiplying by 30. See Methodology in Jails in Indian Country, 2009 for details on estimating expected length of stay. Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 31 Table 4.5 Number of inmates confined in Indian country jails, by demographic characteristic, conviction status, and offense, midyear 2002, 2004, and 2007–2009 Number of inmates held at midyeara Percent of inmates held at midyear Characteristic 2000 2002 2004 2007 2008 2009 2000 2002 2004 2007 2008 2009 Total 1,775 2,006 1,745 1,996 2,135 2,176 100% 100% 100% 100% 100% 100% Sex Male 1,421 1,618 1,346 1,582 1,678 1,754 80% 81% 77% 79% 79% 81% Female 354 388 398 414 457 422 20 19 23 21 21 19 Age group/sex Adults 1,498 1,699 1,546 1,743 1,882 1,919 84% 85% 89% 87% 88% 88% Male 1,214 1,399 1,222 1,415 1,498 1,571 68 70 70 71 70 72 Female 284 300 324 328 384 348 16 15 19 16 18 16 Juveniles 277 307 198 253 253 257 16 15 11 13 12 12 Male 207 219 124 167 180 183 12 11 7 8 8 8 Female 70 88 74 86 73 74 4 4 4 4 3 3 Conviction status Convicted 1,072 1,120 966 1,116 1,340 1,496 61% 57% 58% 59% 63% 69% Unconvicted 689 857 697 763 776 680 39 43 42 41 37 31 Type of offense Domestic violence ... 291 257 362 307 252 ...% 15% 18% 20% 15% 12% Assault ... ... 190 233 308 299 ... ... 13 13 15 15 Rape or sexual assault ... ... 34 45 42 42 ... ... 2 2 2 2 Other violence ... ... 79 108 177 168 ... ... 6 6 9 8 DWI/DUIb 274 226 195 137 184 229 17 11 14 8 9 11 Drug law violation 133 126 104 132 104 107 8 6 7 7 5 5 Other ... ... 569 804 954 955 ... ... 40 44 46 47 Offense not reported ... ... 317 175 59 124 / / / / / / Note: Detailed characteristics may not be equal to the total number of confined inmates because of incomplete data. See appendix tables 1-3 in Jails in Indian Country, 2009, NCJ 232223, BJS Web, February 2011, for a list of all facilities and inmate characteristics. aMidyear count is the number of inmates held on the last weekday in June. bIncludes driving while intoxicated and driving while under the influence of drugs or alcohol. ...Not collected. /Not reported. in facilities that were rated to hold 50 or more inmates, down from 10.3 days in June 2008. Inmates held in jails rated to hold less than 10 inmates experienced the shortest expected length of stay (2.1 days). Inmate characteristics remain relatively unchanged; the number held for domestic violence declined Inmate characteristics by sex, age, and offense have changed in absolute numbers since 2000 (table 4.5). However, the distribution within most categories remained stable between 2000 and 2008, with a change in the distribution of inmates by sex, conviction status, and offense type at midyear 2009. Adult males accounted for the largest portion of the inmate population in Indian country jails during the decade. The female jail population had small but steady increases from midyear 2000 to 2008, with a nearly 8% decrease in the size of this population between midyear 2008 and midyear 2009. Except for one juvenile female inmate, the decline was entirely among the adult female jail population. The percentage of convicted inmates increased from 57% in 2002 to 69% in 2009. Inmates confined for a violent offense made up about 37% of the jail population at midyear 2009, down from 41% at midyear 2008. Most (75%) of this decline was among the population held for domestic violence. Domestic violence (12%) and simple or aggravated assault (15%) accounted for the largest percentage of violent offenders held in 2009, followed by unspecified violent offenses (8%) and rape or sexual assault (2%). Since peaking at midyear 2007, the percentage of inmates held for domestic violence has steadily declined, from 20% in 2007 to 12% in 2009. The Gila River Department of Rehabilitation and Supervision - Adult accounted for a large portion of the decline in domestic violence offenders between 2007 and 2009. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201132 It reported a 38% decrease in the confined inmate population between midyear 2007 (241) and midyear 2009 (149), and a 74% decline in the number of inmates held for a domestic violence (from 180 inmates in 2007 to 46 in 2009). The number of certified correctional officers and in-service training steadily increased Seventy-nine Indian country jails employed 1,332 persons at midyear 2009 (table 4.6). About 69% (916) of all personnel were jail operations staff, including correctional officers and other staff who spent more than 50% of their time supervising inmates. The remaining 416 jail personnel included administrative employees, educational staff, technical or professional staff, clerical, maintenance, or food service staff, and other job functions. Overall, the ratio of inmates to jail operations employees was 2.4 inmates to 1 employee at midyear 2009, remaining relatively stable since 2008 (2.3 to 1) and 2004 (2.5 to 1). Seventy-six facilities reported that 710 (79%) correctional officers received basic detention officer certification, up from 69% in 2008 and 63% in 2007 (not shown). Seventy-four facilities reported that 750 (84%) correctional officers received 40 hours of in-service training, up from 74% in 2008 and 70% in 2007. Table 4.6 Persons employed in Indian country jails, by job function, midyear 2009 Job function Number Percent Totala 1,332 100% Administrativeb 136 10.2% Jail operations 916 68.8 Educational staff 29 2.2 Technical/professional 51 3.8 Clerical/maintenance/food service 173 13.0 Number of inmates per jail operations staff 2.4 aIncludes 27 other persons with unspecified functions not shown in table. bIncludes jail administrators, assistants, and other personnel who work in an administrative capacity more than 50% of the time. Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 33 Methodology The Annual Survey of Jails in Indian Country (SJIC) includes all known Indian country correctional facilities operated by tribal authorities or the Bureau of Indian Affairs (BIA), U.S. Department of the Interior. The survey was conducted in June 2009, and included the number of inmates and percent of capacity occupied based on the ADP, midyear population, and peak population in facilities in June 2009. (See table 10 in Jails in Indian Country, 2009, BJS Web, February 2011.) Through a cooperative agreement with the Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS), Westat, Inc. conducted the SJIC to describe all adult and juvenile jail facilities and detention centers in Indian country. For this report, Indian country includes reservations, pueblos, rancherias, and other appropriate areas (18 U.S.C.§ 1151). The reference date for the survey is June 30, 2009. Annually, BIA provides BJS a list of Indian country jail facilities, including detention centers, jails, and other correctional facilities operated by tribal authorities or BIA. BJS uses this list to update its existing roster of jails in Indian country. BJS obtains data from administrators of Indian country jails by mailed questionnaires and through follow-up phone calls and facsimiles. In 2004, BJS contacted administrators in 70 facilities to participate in the survey. BJS received responses from 61 facilities; 7 did not respond, and 2 facilities were non-operational. In 2007, the BJS roster consisted of 86 facilities. Seventy-nine of the facility administrators responded to the survey; 4 did not respond, and BJS found that 3 facilities were non- operational. In 2008, BJS’s roster of Indian country jails consisted of 85 facilities. BJS received responses from 82 facility administrators; there were no nonrespondents, and 3 facilities were non-operational. For 2009, the BJS roster consisted of 86 facilities. BJS received responses from 80 facility administrators; there were no nonrespondents, and 6 facilities were non-operational. For comparison over time, BJS estimated data on inmate populations for the 7 facilities in 2004 and 4 facilities in 2008 that did not respond to the surveys. Expected length of stay The stock-flow ratio method was used to measure the expected average length of stay for inmates held during June 2009 in the 80 Indian country jails that responded to stock and flow items in the survey: Stock—average daily population Flow—inmate admissions during June 2009 Stock-flow ratio in June 2009 (2,124/11,357=0.187) Expected length of stay in days (0.187 × 30)—is the average number of days held in custody from admission to release. Indian country is a statutory term that includes all lands within an Indian reservation, dependent Indian communities, and Indian trust allotments (18 U.S.C. § 1151). Courts interpret Section 1151 to include all lands held in trust for tribes or their members. (See United States v. Roberts, 185 F.3d 1125 (10th Cir. 1999).) Tribal authority to imprison American Indian offenders is limited to one year per offense by statute (25 U.S.C. § 1302), a $5,000 fine, or both. Tribal law enforcement agencies act as first responders to both felony and misdemeanor crimes. For most of Indian country, the federal government provides felony law enforcement concerning crimes by or against Indians. Certain areas of Indian country are under Public Law 83-280, as amended. P.L. 280 conferred jurisdiction on certain states over Indian country and suspended enforcement of the Major Crimes Act (18 U.S.C. § 1153) and the General Crimes Act (18 U.S.C. § 1152) in those areas. Indian tribes retain concurrent jurisdiction to enforce laws in Indian country where P.L. 280 applies. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201134 Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 35 Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System Mark Motivans, Ph.D., and Howard Snyder, Ph.D., BJS Statisticians The federal criminal justice response to tribal youth varies by the state in which the offense occurred, the nature of the offense, the availability of community- and confinement-based services, and discretionary decisions made by tribal, state, and federal justice agencies. Cases involving tribal youth in the federal system may result in 1) a delinquency adjudication and court-ordered supervision and out-of-home placement, or 2) the youth being transferred to adult status and prosecuted and sentenced as an adult. This summary describes the federal response to tribal youth during the case-processing stages from investigation to corrections. In this report, a federal juvenile delinquent is a person who has committed an offense while under age 18, and the federal prosecutor has certified a federal basis for jurisdiction. Juvenile and youth are used interchangeably in this report. The number of tribal youth in matters concluded by federal prosecutors and the total number of tribal youth prosecuted decreased from 2003 to 2008 (figure 5.1). Tribal youth in matters concluded by federal prosecutors dropped to 115 in 2008, down from 230 in 2003. Highlights � In 2008, relatively few juveniles were referred to federal prosecutors (315 out of 178,570 suspects) or admitted to federal prison jurisdiction (156 out 71,663 offenders). � Tribal youth (70) comprised nearly half of juveniles (152) handled by the federal courts in 2008. � Federal judicial districts of Arizona, Montana, South Dakota, New Mexico, and North Dakota accounted for 94% of tribal youth investigated, 92% of those prosecuted, and 88% of those admitted to federal prison jurisdiction in 2008. � In 2008, about 72% of tribal youth were investigated for violent offenses, including sexual abuse (35%), assault (20%), and murder (17%). � About 40% of matters involving tribal youth were declined by federal prosecutors in 2008. � A greater share of cases involving tribal youth in U.S. district courts were terminated by conviction (91%) than by dismissal (9%). � From 1994 to 2008, the lowest number of tribal (72) and non-tribal youth (84) admitted to the jurisdiction of federal prison authorities occurred in 2008. � Admissions to federal prison jurisdiction among tribal youth declined 10% per year from 1999 to 2008, while non-tribal youth admissions declined 12% per year. � In 2008, tribal youth served an average of 26 months under federal jurisdiction, which was more than double the tribal justice system maximum sentence of 12 months. U.S. Department of Justice Office of Justice Programs Bureau of Justice Statistics June 2011, NCJ 234218 Findings presented in this report are mostly from a recent study conducted by The Urban Institute under a cooperative agreement with the Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS). The study was also sponsored by the Office of Juvenile Justice and Delinquency Prevention (OJJDP). See page 43 for more information. Figure 5.1 Tribal youth in matters concluded and in matters prosecuted by U.S. attorneys, 2000–2008 Number of tribal youth Fiscal year 0 50 100 150 200 250 Suspects in matters prosecuted Suspects in matters concluded 200820072006200520042003200220012000 Source: Urban Institute analysis. See Methodology for more information. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201136 Tracking tribal youth through the stages of the federal criminal case process The federal criminal justice system is not currently well- equipped to monitor how tribal juvenile offenders are processed across stages. There is a lack of unified, system-wide data standards in reporting how youth— especially tribal youth—are handled in the federal system. Juveniles or offenses committed in Indian country are not systematically tracked across the federal justice agencies. Researchers have to devise analytic methods to identify tribal youth using administrative data from each criminal justice stage (arrest, sentencing, and corrections). How is federal jurisdic tion over tribal juvenile delinquents determined? The determination of jurisdiction over offenses occurring in Indian country is first subject to whether state courts have jurisdiction based on Public Law 280 (P.L. 280).1 If a state has P. L. 280 status, jurisdiction over offenses occurring in Indian country lies with the state or tribal courts, not the federal courts. The determination of whether federal jurisdiction applies next depends on the offender and victim in the crime: � If the offender is a juvenile tribal member and the victim is also a tribal member, and the offense is 1 of 15 crimes covered by the Major Crimes Act then jurisdiction is with both the tribal and federal courts.2 � If the offender is a juvenile tribal member and the victim is a non-tribal member, and the crime is covered by the Major Crimes Act or federal enclave status, then federal and tribal courts have shared jurisdiction. The Assimilative Crimes Act permits state law to be applied in federal court where the Major Crimes Act does not apply but federal interest exists. � If the crime involves a non-tribal offender and a tribal member victim, then federal courts have exclusive jurisdiction. Once federal jurisdiction has been established, the Federal Juvenile Delinquency Act (FJDA) provides the procedures to bring the tribal youth to federal court. A federal juvenile delinquent is defined as a person who has committed an offense while less than 18 years old, but has not reached age 21 at sentencing. Juvenile and youth are used interchangeably in this report. How are juveniles handled in the federal justice system? Most juveniles, or persons under age 18, in the United States are handled in state or local courts, which have a separate juvenile justice system, rather than in the federal courts. Federal law permits handling of juveniles in the federal system only in limited circumstances. Apart from those committing crimes in Indian country or on military bases, juveniles that commit offenses as members of drug trafficking gangs, violent criminal gangs, or other federal offenses may be subject to federal jurisdiction. In these cases, the U.S. attorney for each district must certify to the district court that (1) the juvenile court or court of a state does not have jurisdiction or refuses to assume jurisdiction; 2) the state does not have available programs or services adequate for the needs of juveniles; or 3) the offense charged is a felony crime of violence or specified drug offenses, and there is substantial federal interest in the case. I n what circumstances are tribal and non- tribal juveniles transferred to adult status (for prosecution and sentencing as an adult rather than a juvenile delinquent)? Once federal jurisdiction has been determined and certification of delinquency established, a transfer hearing establishes the status of juveniles as to whether they will be transferred for prosecution as an adult. Felony crimes of violence or drug or firearm offenses trigger eligibility for adult transfer with certain age restrictions. Age thirteen is the minimum age for transfer to adult status for murder and assault, and for robbery, bank robbery, or aggravated sexual abuse with a firearm. An exception is crimes committed in Indian country where the tribe has opted not to permit prosecution of juveniles age 13 as adults. Age fifteen is the minimum age for transfer to adult status for committing any crime of violence (including physical force against a person or property). A juvenile can be housed in a Federal Bureau of Prisons (BOP) institution at age 18 if sentenced as an adult. BOP does not operate its own facilities for juveniles; rather, they contract with private entities and state and local governments for both secure and non-secure (community- based) juvenile facilities to house tribal and non-tribal youth under their jurisdiction. 1Congress passed Public Law 280 in 1953, which relinquishes the federal government of criminal and civil jurisdiction in certain states and places jurisdiction with those states. 2The Major Crimes Act provides federal jurisdiction over certain offenses committed by tribal members. (See Title 18 U.S.C. §§ 1152, 1153.) Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 37 Table 5.1 Reason for matters declined for prosecution with tribal youth suspects, 2005–2008 Reasons for declinations Fiscal year Matters concluded Number of declinations Case- relateda Suspect- relatedb No crime Referred to other authoritiesc OtherTotal 2005 172 69 100% 58% 10% 9% 13% 10% 2006 164 80 100% 61 10 10 13 6 2007 143 68 100% 47 15 10 18 10 2008 115 46 100% 50 7 15 20 8 aIncludes weak evidence, stale case, witness problems, or jurisdiction or venue problems. bIncludes age of offender and offender ‘s criminal history and drug/alcohol use. cIncludes pretrial alternative resolutions, such as pretrial diversion. Source: Urban Institute analysis of Executive Office for U.S. Attorneys, National LIONS data base, fiscal years 2005–2008. Investigation and Prosecution Tribal police are often the first to respond to a crime in Indian country. Offenses committed by tribal youth may be investigated by a combination of tribal police and federal law enforcement agencies. The federal Bureau of Investigation (FBI) and the Bureau of Indian Affairs (BIA) are the primary federal law enforcement agencies investigating tribal youth matters. Tribal youth commonly enter the federal justice system with an arrest for a warrant issued on either a complaint or juvenile information (written accusation made by the prosecutor). For serious offenses that may indicate a federal crime, the U.S. attorney’s office in the district is notified as is the juvenile’s parent/guardian. The juvenile must be taken before a U.S. magistrate as soon as possible, where charges are read and the juvenile is informed of rights. Federal prosecutors next determine if the matter should be adjudicated in federal courts, disposed by U.S. magistrate, or declined for prosecution. In 2008, 4 in 10 matters involving a tribal youth were declined by federal prosecutors During 2008, 40% of tribal youth in matters concluded were declined for further prosecution, which was lower than the 46% declination rate for non-tribal youth in 2008. However, the average declination rate for tribal youth (45%) was higher than for non- tribal youth (37%) from 2004 to 2008. The most common reason for declination of tribal youth matters in 2008 was case related (50%) (table 5.1). Case-related reasons included weak evidence, stale case, witness problems, and jurisdiction or venue problems (figure 5.2). Some declined matters involved tribal youth that were subsequently referred to other authorities for prosecution, such as to the tribe or the state where the tribe is located. The share of declinations for tribal youth that were referred to other authorities or received an alternative resolution increased from 13% of all declinations in 2005 to 20% in 2008. Among non-tribal youth, the most common reason for declination (71%) was that the suspect was a juvenile (not shown in table). Most tribal youth in matters referred to U.S. attorneys were prosecuted by federal prosecutors In 2008, 59% of tribal youth who were referred to federal prosecutors were prosecuted, which was higher than the 54% prosecution rate for non-tribal youth in 2008 (including matters disposed by U.S. magistrates). From 2004 to 2008, the averageprosecution rate for tribal youth (55%) was comparable to that of non-tribal youth (53%). Various factors go into the decision to prosecute a matter, including seriousness of the crime, strength of the evidence, youth’s criminal history and drug/alcohol use, tribal capacity to prosecute, and tribal preference. Tribes having concurrent jurisdiction with federal jurisdiction may have limitations on available secure placement options and treatment resources. The potential penalty that could be received if a matter was handled in tribal or state venues may also be considered.3 3The Indian Civil Rights Act (Title 25 U.S.C. § 1302(7)), for example, limited tribes in sentencing persons convicted of serious crimes to a maximum of 1 year in jail and a $5,000 fine. Recently, the Tribal Law and Order Act extended the maximum sentence that a tribe can impose to three years. Figure 5.2 Case-related reasons for matters declined for prosecution with tribal youth suspects, 2005–2008 Jurisdiction or venue problems Stale case Witness problems Weak evidence Percent of cases 77% 13% 8% 2% Source: Urban Institute analysis of Executive Office for U.S. Attorneys, National LIONS data base, fiscal years 2005–2008. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201138 Nearly 9 of 10 tribal youth admitted to Federal Bureau of Prisons jurisdiction from 2006 to 2008 came from five federal judicial districts From 2006 to 2008, 85% of tribal youth admitted to the jurisdiction of the Federal Bureau of Prisons (BOP) were from these five federal judicial districts: Arizona, Montana, New Mexico, North Dakota, and South Dakota (figure 5.3). The most recent tribal population data from the Bureau of Indian Affairs (2005) showed that these five districts contained 12% of the 590 federally recognized tribal entities and 35% of the more than 1.9 million total tribal enrollment population (table 5.2). Thirty-four percent of the enrolled tribal population under age 16 resided on or near reservations in these five federal judicial districts. Table 5.2 Federally recognized tribes and enrolled members, 2005 Tribal entities Tribal enrollment Tribal population under age 16 Federal judicial district Number Percent Number Percent District rank Number Percent of total enrollment District rank Total 590 100% 1,978,099 100% ~ 503,958 100% ~ Arizona 22 3.7% 269,778 13.6% 2 70,854 14.1% 2 New Mexico 25 4.2 174,199 8.8 3 43,234 8.6 4 South Dakota 8 1.4 115,513 5.8 5 27,534 5.5 6 Montana 8 1.4 66,962 3.4 6 14,957 3 9 North Dakota 6 1 58,220 2.9 8 13,851 2.7 10 All other districts 521 88.3 1,293,427 65.4 ~ 333,528 66.2 ~ ~Not available. Source: U.S. Department of the Interior, Bureau of Indian Affairs. American Indian Population and Labor Force Report, 2005, available at: http://www.bia.gov/ WhatWeDo/Knowledge/Reports/index.htm, calendar year 2005. 45–87 16–4416–44 1–151–15 0 District of Arizona (14%) District of New Mexico (12%) District of Montana (28%) District of North Dakota (4%) District of South Dakota (27%) Number of tribal youth admitted Figure 5.3 Tribal youth admitted to the jurisdiction of the Federal Bureau of Prisons, and five federal judicial districts that committed the majority of tribal youth, 2006–2008 Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics analysis of data from the Federal Bureau of Prisons, SENTRY database, fiscal years 2006–2008. Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 39 Adjudication and Sentencing Federal statutes provide for a youth’s release pending trial to a parent/ guardian, unless it is determined that detention is necessary to ensure a timely appearance or to ensure safety of juveniles or others (Title 18 U.S.C. § 5034). The federal pretrial services agency oversees supervision of the youth on pretrial release. For juveniles detained, a foster home or community-based facility near the youth’s home community is sought. Pretrial juveniles are not to be detained in facilities permitting regular contact with adult offenders nor with other juveniles who have been adjudicated. In 2008, 91% of cases terminated in U.S. district court involving tribal youth resulted in conviction Most (91%) tribal youth cases terminated ended in conviction in 2008. Most of the convictions were the result of a guilty plea (88%) than a determination of guilt at trial (3%). In comparison, 95% of non-tribal youth were convicted in 2008, with 91% resulting from guilty pleas and 5% following trial. From 2004 to 2008, the average conviction rate for tribal youth (92%) was higher than for non- tribal youth (87%). In juvenile adjudication proceedings, the judge has the discretion to impose an out-of-home placement, probation and conditions of probation, or restitution. The youth may also be transferred to adult status and prosecuted and sentenced as an adult. An adjudicated juvenile can receive up to 3 years of probation. The duration of a sentence for youth adjudicated delinquent to the jurisdiction of federal prison authorities depends on the age of the juvenile at disposition (see text box below). Juveniles under the age of 18 are not allowed to be placed in an institution in which the youth has regular contact with incarcerated adults. A juvenile can be housed in a Federal Bureau of Prisons (BOP) institution at the age of 21 if sentenced as a juvenile. The maximum time under federal jurisdiction of juveniles adjudicated delinquent depends on the age at disposition � If a juvenile was under 18 years of age at time of disposition, detention may not extend beyond the juvenile reaching age 21 (figure 5.4). � If a juvenile was between the ages of 18 and 21 at time of disposition, the maximum federal jurisdiction is 5 years. � Juveniles adjudicated delinquent and under the age of 21 are not to be detained in facilities permitting regular contact with adult convicts. At age 21, however, an adjudicated delinquent can be placed in an adult facility. � The term that an adjudicated delinquent receives may not exceed the maximum period of imprisonment authorized had the juvenile been an adult. Federal sentencing guidelines do not apply to adjudications of delinquency. 11 or younger 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 Maximum age in federal jurisdiction is 21 if age at disposition is under 18 years Age at disposition Maximum age of federal jurisdiction For disposition between ages 18 and 21, the maximum length of federal jurisdiction is 5 years Age of delinquent at disposition Figure 5.4 Maximum time under federal jurisdiction of juveniles adjudicated delinquent, by age at disposition Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201140 Corrections The number of tribal youth admitted to BOP jurisdiction increased from 107 in 1994 to a peak of 252 in 2000— a 136% increase due exclusively to the growth in tribal youth handled as adjudicated delinquents (figure 5.5). The number of tribal youth admitted to the BOP subsequently decreased from 252 in 2000 to 72 in 2008. In 2008, the number of tribal (72) and non-tribal youth (84) admitted to the jurisdiction of federal prison authorities was the lowest in the period from 1994 to 2008. From 1999 to 2008, the number of tribal youth admissions declined an annual average of 10%, and non-tribal admissions declined at an annual average of 12%. Tribal youth peaked at 252 admissions in 2000, and non- tribal youth peaked at 272 admissions in 1999 (figure 5.6). Most (88%) of the decline in tribal youth from 1999 to 2008 was due to a decrease in youth who had been adjudicated delinquent. Twelve percent of the decline was due to a decrease in tribal youth who had been transferred to adult status. In comparison, most of the decline for non-tribal youth admitted to the BOP over this period was comprised of juveniles who had been transferred to adult status. In 2008, 72% of tribal youth were admitted to BOP jurisdiction for a violent offense, including sexual abuse (29%), assault (25%), and murder (15%) (table 5.3). Tribal youth admitted for property offenses (mostly burglary) peaked in 2000 (66) and began to decline in 2001, dropping to 14 admissions in 2008. By 2008, tribal youth admitted to BOP jurisdiction for both property and violent offenses had declined to the lowest levels since 1999. Among non-tribal youth admitted to BOP jurisdiction, violent and drug offenses comprised the majority of offense types (not shown in table). Most tribal youth admitted to BOP jurisdiction from 1999 to 2008 had been adjudicated delinquent (83%), while most non-tribal youth had been prosecuted as adults (65%). 0 50 100 150 200 250 300 Tribal-transferred as adult Tribal-adjudicated delinquent 200820072006200520042003200220012000199919981997199619951994 Number of tribal youth Fiscal year Figure 5.5 Tribal youth admitted to the jurisdiction of the Federal Bureau of Prisons, by status at admission, 1994–2008 Note: Data for fiscal years 1999–2008 based on Urban Institute analysis of Federal Bureau of Prisons, SENTRY database. Data for fiscal years 1994–1998 based on BJS analysis of SENTRY data. 0 50 100 150 200 250 300 Non-tribal-transferred as adult Non-tribal-adjudicated delinquent 200820072006200520042003200220012000199919981997199619951994 Number of non-tribal youth Fiscal year Figure 5.6 Non-tribal youth admitted to the jurisdiction of the Federal Bureau of Prisons, by status at admission, 1994–2008 Note: Data for fiscal years 1999–2008 based on Urban Institute analysis of Federal Bureau of Prisons, SENTRY database. Data for fiscal years 1994–1998 based on BJS analysis of SENTRY data. Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 41 At yearend 2003, 298 tribal youth were in BOP facilities, including both juvenile contract and adult facilities In 2003, 74% of tribal youth were housed under BOP jurisdiction in Minnesota, Arizona, Utah, the Western District of Texas, and Colorado. BOP facilities (including contract facilities) were not located in the states that contained large tribal populations and had committed a large number of Indian country juveniles (South Dakota, North Dakota, Montana, and New Mexico). For example, tribal youth whose legal residence was South Dakota comprised over half of the juveniles in BOP facilities in Minnesota. Among tribal youth under BOP jurisdiction in 2003, most were committed for a violent felony offense, including homicide, manslaughter, serious sexual assault or abuse, and serious physical assault. In comparison, 185 tribal juveniles were in custody in 10 juvenile tribal facilities in 2002. (See American Indians and Crime, BJS Web, December 2004.) These tribal youth were confined mostly for misdemeanor (62%) and status offenses (29%); 10% of the youth were confined in tribal juvenile facilities for felony offenses. Table 5.3 Tribal youth admitted to the jurisdiction of the Federal Bureau of Prisons, 1999–2008 Year of commitment to BOP jurisdiction Commitment offense Total 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 2008 Total 1,909 241 252 219 234 212 231 208 164 76 72 Murder/Negligent manslaughter* 218 31 27 25 18 20 24 26 20 16 11 Assault 491 44 65 70 57 52 64 52 49 20 18 Robbery 51 7 5 9 4 7 9 4 3 1 2 Sexual abuse 441 55 52 33 65 46 55 57 40 17 21 Embezzlement 1 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 Burglary 442 62 66 59 61 53 43 42 30 12 14 Larceny 56 12 7 5 8 4 4 6 6 2 2 Motor vehicle theft 8 2 1 1 0 1 0 1 2 0 0 Arson and explosives 69 2 6 3 5 11 17 9 6 7 3 Other property offenses 38 13 6 6 4 1 3 3 1 1 0 Other drug felonies 3 0 1 0 0 1 0 1 0 0 0 Weapon offenses 9 1 2 0 2 1 2 1 0 0 0 Nonviolent sex offenses 36 4 4 1 4 7 7 3 5 0 1 Traffic offenses 13 2 5 1 1 3 1 0 0 0 0 Note: Total includes juveniles whose offenses were missing or unclassifiable. *Includes attempted murder. Source: Urban Institute analysis of Federal Bureau of Prisons, SENTRY data base, fiscal years 1999-2008. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201142 Tribal youth served a sentence in federal facilities that was twice as long as the maximum sentence tribal facilities can impose From 1999 to 2008, the average time served by tribal youth tended to be longer (about 26 months, on average) than the tribal justice system maximum sentence of 12 months. The Tribal Law and Order Act of 2010 recently extended the maximum a tribal court can sentence to 3 years for those courts meeting conditions placed on the legal process. The average time served by non-tribal youth in BOP facilities more than doubled from 15 months in 1999 to over 38 months by 2008. Non-tribal youth admitted to the federal prison authorities were somewhat more dispersed than tribal youth with respect to district of commitment About 32% of non-tribal youth were committed from the five federal districts that committed the most tribal youth. Thirty-six percent of non-tribal youth were committed to the BOP from five federal judicial districts along the U.S.-Mexico border: California-Southern, Arizona, New Mexico, Texas-Western, and Texas-Southern. (figure 5.7). Among juveniles admitted to the jurisdiction of the BOP in 2008, non- tribal youth were slightly older at age of offense than tribal youth The average of age tribal youth at time of offense was about 15 years compared to 16 years for non-tribal youth. Most tribal youth were male (92%), American Indian (96%), non- Hispanic (99%), and United States citizens (100%). The majority of non- tribal youth were male (93%), white (60%), non-Hispanic (58%), and United States citizens (71%). 26–6026–60 10–2510–25 1–91–9 00 Number of non-tribal youth admittedNumber of non-tribal youth admitted District of Arizona (19%) New Mexico (5%) District of Western Texas (7%) District of Eastern New York (4%)District of South Dakota (3%) Figure 5.7 Non-tribal youth admitted to the jurisdiction of the Federal Bureau of Prisons, and five federal judicial districts that committed the majority of non-tribal youth, 2006–2008 Source: Based on BJS analysis of data from the Federal Bureau of Prisons, SENTRY database, fiscal years 2006–2008. Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 43 Methodology The primary source of data presented in this report is from the Federal Justice Statistics Program (FJSP). The methodology to identify tribal youth was developed by the Urban Institute, and primary findings reported here are drawn from their 2011 study, Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System (http://ncjrs.gov). This report supplemented findings from the Urban Institute’s study with additional analyses based on BJS analysis of FJSP data. Data from the Federal Bureau of Prisons (BOP), SENTRY database, which contains information on all federally sentenced offenders admitted to BOP jurisdiction at fiscal yearend were analyzed for the years 1994 to 1998. The source of the data in figure 5.1 is The Urban Institute analysis of Executive Office for U.S. Attorneys, National LIONS database, fiscal years 2000 to 2008. Suspects in matters concluded include all matters which were concluded in each respective year. Suspects in matters prosecuted include matters for which the U.S. attorneys in that district made the decision to prosecute the matter in each fiscal year. The unit of count for figure 5.1 is the suspect matter. A matter is a referral on which an attorney spends one hour or more investigating, and on which formal papers have not been filed with the Court. If a decision is made not to continue with the investigation, it is disposed of in the LIONS database by declination and closed. References American Indians and Crime, NCJ 203097, BJS Web, December 2004. 2005 American Indian Population and Labor Force Report. U.S. Department of the Interior, Bureau of Indian Affairs, 2005. The Urban Institute. Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System, NCJ 234549, May 2011. Available at http://ncjrs.gov. Researchers from The Urban Institute investigated how youth from Indian Country were processed by the federal criminal justice system. They used a combination of qualitative and quantitative information, including administrative data from the BJS-sponsored Federal Justice Statistics Program (FJSP) and information drawn from interviews with more than three dozen federal and tribal justice system personnel. Staff at the Urban Institute who contributed to the study included— Co-principal Investigators William Adams and Julie Samuels Contextual Analysis Team Janeen Buck Willison Hannah Dodd Meredith Dank Quantitative Analysis Team Barbara Parthasarathy Kamala Mallik Kane Jessica Kelly Sybil Mendonca KiDeuk Kim Office of Justice Programs Innovation • Partnerships • Safer Neighborhoods http://www.ojp.gov work_3wezn5cw7vam3oz6g7vj3pu67m ---- correspondence "JUSTICE AND THE INTERNATIONAL COURT" In a letter to the editor, Charles Burton Marshall wrote that, "Like many comments critical of the judgment of the International Court of justice in the South West Africa case, worldview's editorial [July- August] seems to me to confuse law in the sense of procedural rectitude applied in litigation and law as policy enacted into legislation." Mr. Marslwdl elab- orated his own views in a letter to the Honorable E. Rose Adair. What follows is the text of that letter as it was introduced into the O'Hara subcommittee hearing record. Another, and differing, opinion is suggested bij Ernest A. Gross, recently chief counsel to Liberia and Ethiopia in the case before the International Court. His article, "The South Africa Case: What Happened," appears in Foreign Affairs, October 1966. Arlington, Va. Dear Mr. Adair: This letter follows on our conversation about the judgment of the International Court of Justice con- cluding the long and complex litigation in the South West Africa case, the outcome of which seemed to come as a surprise to a great many, including, ac- cording to his own acknowledgement, the Secretary of State. I am astonished by the evidence of astonishment. Prompted by professional curiosity and free of con- scious preconceptions, I had examined the labyrin- thine issues as developed in a dozen printed volumes of varying bulk and a mass of transcribed oral argu- ment put forth by the litigants. Whatever facet I examined closely, the weight of the argument seemed to me clearly on the respondent's—that is, South Africa's—side. Accordingly, I rather expected South Africa to prevail finally. Foresight in such a matter, however, requires tak- ing count of judges as well as taking account of. legal points. On this basis, the respondent seemed to me definitely the favorite and the petitioning side, Ethi- opia and Liberia, a palpable long shot. Let me ex- plain. The potential participants in the decision included fifteen regular members-of the Court and two ad hoc judges named by the respective sides—seventeen in all. One regular judge stood aside, presumably in appropriate regard for the fact of having once been designated ad hoc judge for the petitioners before election as a regular judge. Another was removed by illness, and a third by death. Thus the residual num- ber nearing the decisive stage was fourteen. .That even number presented a possibility of a We, in which event, under the law as laid down in the Court's statute, it would fall to the presiding fudge to resolve the issue by casting a second vote. Of the residual fourteen at this stage, four judges were participating in the case for the first time, whereas ten had participated at a preliminary, though substantive, stage four years ago, when the Court had divided eight to seven on whether the petition- ers had standing as such and whether their petition presented a justiciable issue. Six of the seven then dissenting were among the ten. Their number in- cluded the presiding judge, authorized to break a tie. Only four of the eight prevailing in the prelimi- nary stage remained. If all six previous dissentients abided by their earlier views, the addition of only one from among the four judges newly participating would produce the tie that would in effect constitute a shifted major- ity. By the same token, all four of the new particip- ants must align with the four remnant from the earlier majority to produce again a majority tfor the petitioners. Superficially considered, the prospect presented a 15-to-l probability in favor of South Africa. One must, however, look deeper than the superficial data. What was the probability of a shift among the six previous dissenters? To judge by the unequivocal- ness of the positions articulated on the record, the solid legal analysis reflected in diem, and their con- tinuing central bearing on the case, such a probabil- ity seemed negligible. What was the probability that one, just one, of the new participants would align himself with them? Getting down to a particular, why assume that Judge Cros of France would not reflect views akin to those ably articulated in 1962 by his predecessor also of France, Judge Basdevant? I could think of no reason so to assume. Tims, under closer analysis, the 15-to-l odds seemed conservative indeed I come back to the Secretary of State's acknowl- edged surprise. Surely no one would criticize so over- pressed an official for not having delved for himself into such details. In such matters he must rely on advices from below. What interests me here, then, is the quality of bureaucratically generated informa- tion. October 1966 7 On a half dozen or so occasions within a span of a few weeks preceding the decision, the South West Africa case came up in conversation with one person or another well up in the State Department. Invari- ably I was told something to the effect mat it looked bad for South Africa or was asked how else conceiv- ably could the Court rule? When I pressed for de- tails to support that outlook, I was told something to the effect that such was the overwhelming consensus among those close to the matter. In a context like that, consensus is very likely to be synonymous with gossip. Solid information is,all too likely to be a shaky, wishful guess, built up to apparent authority by being circulated through departmental channels as through an induction coil. Such was probably the case here. Very often in a bureaucracy the least re- liable index to what is what is what comes from the office most concerned. In testifying on May 17 before the subcommittee on Africa, I purposely refrained from venturing a prediction of the outcome, regarding it as insolent for an outsider to anticipate in public regarding such matters. I did utter a caution against an idea, urged by earlier witnesses, calling for the United States ostentatiously to get poised to set in motion plans based on a guessed-at outcome, which seemed so unlikely to materialize. Such conduct could only put the Government in a posture of attempting to prej- udice an issue sub judice, a foolish posture at best. Fortunately, our magistrates avoided that gau- cherie. Behind the scenes, an amusing thing oc- curred, however, and some of my State Department friends, later shared the laugh with me. On the Fri- day preceding the decision, the State Department did send to die government at Pretoria a formal note, declaring the United States' devout concern for the rule of law in international relations and serving solemn notice of an intent to spare no ef- fort to enforce the forthcoming decision. What is comical about this painstaking flaunting of unexcep- tional precepts is the reflection of misguided antici- pation. Obviously, initiative still outruns urbanity in our diplomacy, There is a need to ponder Talley- rand's sagacity—"above all, not too much zeal." The South African authorities probably could not imagine a great power's resorting to such a step without conclusive advance knowledge of the out- come. Accordingly, the note's arrival may well have shaken momentarily their confidence—which my wife and I found so secure and ernphatic when we pri- vately discussed the case with some of them last April—of a judgment favorable to South Africa. Whatever the misgivings temporarily incurred, it must be regarded by them now as clearly to the good, from South Africa's standpoint, to have in hand an unequivocal expression from the U.S. Gov- ernment pledging to honor the decision and calling it good, sight unseen. Indeed, the decision is good, and I say this from an American standpoint. It serves to dissipate some of the obfuscation surrounding the broader South African question. It removes a main promise relied on by those who have hoped and striven to inveigle the United States obliquely into an improvident in- terposition in South Africa's internal affairs. It di- minishes substantially the chance of involving the United States in needless conflict at a time when— Heaven knows!—it is already experiencing its por- tion of travail elsewhere. I say that the decision re- duces the probability of yet another outbreak of in- ternational violence—notwithstanding that some who had looked expectantly to the International Court for a decision that they could invoke as a warrant for precipitating violence now assert, in the wake of the decision issued, that the outcome leaves them no alternative to violence. Such talk coming from spokesmen for some of the other African states is discountable as rhetoric. The South African Republic should be able to cope with anything its piqued northward neighbors might try, as those neighbors are amply aware. To any importunities to fetch chestnuts from the fire for them, our Government is now in position explicitly to say: the chestnuts are not ours. Our high policy- makers no longer need to feel pressed and reproached by invocations of a shadowy legal obligation in such matters. The outcome, as The Washington Post prop- erly observed in the sole fairly cogent editorial I saw on the matter, puts the South Africa question squarely in the political field where, if anywhere, it belongs. Our policy-makers would not bo in po- sition to invoke any exculpatory abstractions con- cerning fealty to the rule of law if they should here- after precipitate us into a blunder in that connec- tion. It is scarcely imaginable now—indeed it never was—that our magistrates would indulge in such im- prudence The sooner this is quietly made clear across Africa, the better for everybody. I stress quietly. The thing to do is to simmer down—to quit talking so much about matters that we are so little likely to do much of anything about, unless we take leave of our gumption. A few observations are due concerning the qual- ity of the Court's decision and. the pertinent opin- ions. The opinion delivered by the presiding judge, Sir Percy Spender, strikes me as a superb judicial 8 worldvieto exercise, equal in quality to the erudite and essen- tially right opinion in which he and Sir Gerald Fitz- maurice as dissenters combined at the prelimin;iry stage in 1962. It is good to see such wisdom ele- vated from a losing to a prevailing position. In such a legal controversy, it is necessary for the petitioning side to construct a chain of reasoning long enough to reach from the initial premise to the conclusion sought. If one link fails, the chain fails as determinatively as if every link should give way. A respondent needs to demolish only one link- in the essential chain in order to prevail. Courts are wisely reluctant to carry the adjudicative func- tion to excess. It is standard judicial practice to re- solve only such issues as are necessary to dispose of a case, the maxim being that when it is not nec- essary to decide it is necessary, not to decide. The petitioners' first link crumbled under judicial analy- sis. So the Court has left the matter there, A headline I saw in The New York Times called the basis of decision a technicality. The dictionary's relevant definition is: "something which is techni- cal; especially, a point of law, detail of procedure, rule, etc., of significance only to a technician." The term is often used in controverted matters dispar- agingly; one side's point of substance is a techni- cality to the opposing side. When a chain of legal reasoning snaps, the losing side is wont to say that only one link went—and it but a technicality. Like other disciplines, however, law is a fabric woven of technicalities. In a legal context, to call something technically defective is to call it legally defective. To say that the petition was rejected on a techni- cality is just a way of saying that it lacked accept- ability as a proposition in law, but by the use of that word the pejorative implication is shifted from the petition to the decision, I noted that word in the headline with amuse- ment at another instance of editorializing in a news account. Then a high spokesman in our foreign pol- icy—why name him?—used the same term in the same connection, Noting it that time, I disapproved heartily. If that overpressed official should ever find occasion to familiarize himself with the opinion, his misimpression will be corrected. The basis of deci- sion was a matter of substantive law. The presiding judge's opinion makes the point amply clear. The applicants were found to have no legal right or in- terest in the subject matter of their claims. A tech- nicality? Maybe so. It would depend on the inflec- tion used. If one means a mere technicality, then no. Such a basis for a judicial finding is about as substantive as one can get. A related notion widely repeated by persons un- familiar with the relevant opinions, having to rely therefore on news media for their evaluations, echoes Judge Jcssup's highly publicized declaration, in dis- sent, labeling "the Judgment which the Court has just rendered . . . completely unfounded in law." Obviously, if he considered the judgment otherwise than as he describes it, he would concur instead of dissenting. Boiled down to its essence, the quoted assertion conveys only the fact of Judge Jessup's disagreement with the prevailing side. He registers his view in the style customary in judicial polemics. Like anyone else, a judge dislikes being among the losers. In the immediate moment of disappointment he is likely to display pique by choosing dramatic language. Moreover, a dissenting judge casts him- self as advocate for an overruled cause, and advo- cacy requires a combative approach. In Judge Jes- sup's instance, disappointment is heavy indeed. He feels deprived of an opportunity to go all the way with the petitioners. Notwithstanding the presiding judge's appeal for colleagues to focus their ap- pended essays on the determining element in the case and to avoid laboring the might-have-beens, Judge Jessup's essay examines approvingly all the links in the snapped} chain. His considerable skills in advocacy arc displayed to the full. (In a concur- ring opinion South Africa's ad hoc judge, J, T. van Wyk, labors similarly to show how he thinks each of those links might have been sundered in its turn if the Court had to go on to deal with them. His and Judge Jessup's extensive essays in advocacy have at least the value of rounding out the record by exploring all the controverted ramifications.) As a related point, it is not correct-though I have noted several misguided allegations to the contrary —that the element on which the decision turns was properly disposed of once and for all in the 1962 stage of the proceedings. The idea is palpably false. To utter it is like saying, on meeting an acquaint- ance after a considerable interval, "But I thought you were deadl Aren't you? I couldn't have been wrong!" Nor is it correct diat the Court, besides resurrecting the element on which the decision foc- used, heard no fresh argument on it. The element remained an inherent issue throughout, and it was argued by counsel as searchingly if not as lengdi- ily, in the latter stages as in the preliminary phase. What has happened essentially is a shift in deter- mining numbers. It is not so much a case of the Court's changing its mind, Different minds have changed the Court. The old dissenters have become the new prevailers, acceding thus to the right to call October I960 9 themselves the Court. As one of them puts it, "The Court is not bound to perpetuate faulty reasoning, and nothing contained in the 1962 Judgment could constitute a decision on any issue which is a part of the merits of the claim." Yet another criticism widely voiced pertains to the six-year interval between onset and upshot. Is it fair, the critics ask, to let petitioners protract false expectations so long—to withhold bad news until so late. {A teacher often hears similar plaints from students denied a degree after long endeavor.) The point is psychologically understandable. Those who launched the case felt so certain of a verdict that the outcome leaves them with a sense of being jilted. The right to attempt a suit is not a right to a favorable judgment, however. The long wait and final letdown would never have occurred if the peti- tioners had not launched a complex litigation on a dubious premise. No one compelled, or even en- ticed, them into a vain suit and false hopes. In all that interval the petitioners have been denied noth-. ing rightfully theirs. The criticism reminds me of a magazine agent who once told me I bad just wasted a half-hour of his time. Anodier reproach is that the decision is political. That last is a tricky word, a catchall pertaining to aspects of public affairs involving highly contro- verted interests and conflicts of purpose between or among large groups, with no established, accepted frame of values by which to settle the matter at issue, to the general satisfaction, at hand. The word political pertains to the processes by which such matters arise, and such controversies are waged, managed, and perhaps finally brought to solution. In any proper sense of the word the South West Africa case is inherently political. The sponsors of the petition are politically actuated. What they have sought is a judicial writ to use as a political weap- on. I am not calling this reprehensible. I am just saying it is so. So also is the respondent politically motivated. One cannot examine any facet of the case without finding matters which are inextricably political. When someone on the side whose interests did not prevail calls the decision political, one can only remark, "Look who's talking!" Obviously, also the Court's decision has a political effect. It alters the frame of the dispute about South West Africa and thus indirectly about South Africa as well, just as it would alter the frame of dispute if the deci- sion were in the opposed direction. Those who would attack the Court's judgment as political only reflect their disappointment that the Court, in inter- preting the law, did not fashion a decision to suit their political designs. 10 worldview In this respect, the Court's judgment seems to me altogether salutary. It is beyond the Court's province to stay the current widespread urge to make every- body's business everybody's business over the great globe, but the effect of the Court's judgment is to put a damper on the fashion of parading that urge under a rule-of-law rubric. Not everyone who fancies a grievance has therefore a case. The Court exists to apply the rules scrupulously as valid cases come to it, but its mission is not to issue hunting licenses for dissatisfied governments to go stalking in other people's preserves. The Court is disposed to remain a Court, not to be tempted to set itself up as a leg- islature. Such are some of the points implicit in the South West Africa judgment. One can only hope that a determining number.of governments, includ- ing our own, will come to recognize the eminent good sense of that position and to discern that the judgment preserves, rather than sacrificing, the Court's usefulness. As knowledge of the nature of thfe pleadings re- jected by the Court widens, many-persons now dis- posed to be critical about the judgment may well come to see its essential wisdom. I refer here par- ticularly to the interpretation of pertinent matters put forth by the applicants after the respondent had succeeded in refuting the original premises of the application and the accompanying allegations re- garding performance under the mandate. The inter- pretation thereupon resorted to by the applicants would have the Court assume powers of a legisla- tive character not entertained in the instrument. which created it. The Court, moreover, would be called upon to attribute to General Assembly reso- lutions a law-making import not warranted by the United Nations Charter. In the name of the rule of law, the Court was thus importuned to contrive new law to suit the applicants' ends. In determining num- ber, the judges have declined to presume a preroga- tive not j-ightfully theirs or to read into the Charter an intent which the Charter does not in fact reflect. If the judges were compelled to go as far as to ad- dress themselves to that issue in resolving the case, they would have to choose between a judicial ar- rogation and an implicit extension of judicial ap- proval to South Africa's policies. At such a juncture, the Court would indeed take on a political char- acter. That juncture has been avoided, for the Court has found ample basis for resolving the case on an antecedent, though centrally important, aspect. This is not to say, in any invidious way, that the Court's resolution of the case is politically motivated. In face of great pressures, the judges of the Inter- national Court of Justice in determining number have kept to the best tradition of jurisprudence, thereby reconfirming for the institution the esteem which I recall having heard Chairman O'Hara voice so succinctly at one of the hearings of the subcom- mittee on Africa. Indeed, a matter for which the prevailing judges deserve great credit is their re- sistance to becoming politicized in handling a case inescapably charged with politics. It is no detrac- tion from the value and the conclusiveness of the decision that the outcome was determined by the presiding judge's breaking of a tie, though one of the dissenting judges faintly attempts to make a point on this score, The rules constraining the Court in thus resolving the case are as basic to its struc- ture as is the judge's right to voice his dissent. Thank you for inviting my attention to The Con- gressional Record reporting Chairman O'Hara's well chosen words occasioned by the judgment. They display a balance between specific immediate regret over the outcome and a general disposition to re- spect the institution and its processes, and the ef- fect is consistent with the Chairman's remarks al- luded to above. I am reminded, by contrast, of a TV interview in which someone speaking for the ap- plicants characterized the Court's judgment as a "judicial abortion." Someone identified with a mis- conceived and miscarried case is likely thus to choose terms calculated to shift fault from the case itself to the outcome, much as a strongly motivated ball player often inveighs against the umpire on be- ing called out in attempting to steal a base. The re- actions voiced by the applicant governments them- selves and some of the governments associated with them in supporting the venture to elicit a court de- cision for use in a political cause have been in sim- ilar vein. One is reminded of the way fans in Flat- bush used to react when the old Dodgers dropped a ball game. I am prompted to a thought about style in being on the losing side in international litigation. A few years ago a friend of mine, who is a distinguished member of the bar and a statesman of high repute, represented a Southeast Asian government in a case before the International Court of Justice growing out of a dispute with a neighboring country over a certain parcel of land. His side won the judgment. The other side recriminated strenuously on the "we- wuz-robbed" theme. My friend was scornful of such conduct. He remarked to me his confidence that there would have been no such reaction if the de- cision had gone the other way. He told of having taken upon himself as counsel a duty to instruct his clients in the nature of judicial processes and the character of judicial resolution of controversies. A disputant tends to sec only his own side of the case, thus to define justice in terms of his own interests. He is all too likely to regard a court as morally and legally bound to see the issues his way. A ca- pacity to surprise litigants is inherent in the judicial process. My friend had impressed these points upon his clients. He had advised them about expecting the unexpected and had made clear to them how to comport themselves in event of an adverse ruling. "The rule of law, after all, is not merely an abstrac- tion in the judges' custody," he remarked to me. "It is also, and even more importantly, an attitude of mind among adversaries and a mode of behavior in concrete situations." CHARLES BURTON MARSHALL London, England Dear Sir: In your very interesting issue for July- August there is an editorial "Justice and the Inter- national Court," which seems to me to make the case appear even worse than it actually is. What the Court did was to declare that Ethiopia and Liberia, which had brought the case to the Court, were not entitled to do so, and that they had no status as appellants. This of course was an extraordinary de- cision, since quite the opposite had been taken in 1962 and it means that the rights and wrongs of the case never came before the Court at all. The Court ha* tlierefore made no decision for or against the case'but has declined to discuss it when brought before them by two individual countries. It would, however, be perfectly in order for the U.N. itself to bring the case before the Court, the only difficulty being tliat as it could not be called a dispute they could only ask for an advisory opin- ion, and this of course has not got the force of law. However, it looks as though the African countries at the U.N. Assembly are going to ask for a good- deal more than this, and we shall have to wait and see what happens. In the meantime I think it is very important to emphasize the fact that the World Court has not taken a decision about S. Africa and its mandate for S.W. Africa, merely because it would not accept Ethiopia and Liberia as having a right to bring cases to the Court, because they have no status as individual countries. D A M E KATHLEEN COURTNEY, D.B.E. October 1966 11 work_43anyane6jcehjzn7w6orxrbbi ---- JUSTICE, GENDER AND INTERNATIONAL BOUNDARIES JUSTICE. GENDER AND INTERNATIONAL BOUNDARIES Onora O'Neill. University of Essex, May 1989 1. JUSTICE FOR IMPOVERISHED PROVIDERS Questions about Justice to women and about international Justice are often raised in discussions of development. Yet many influential theories of Justice have difficulty in handling either topic. I shall first compare some theoretical difficulties that have arisen in these two domains, and then sketch an account of Justice that may be better suited to handling questions both of gender and of international Justice. I begin by distinguishing idealized from relativized theories of Justice. Idealized accounts of Justice stress the need to abstract from the particularities of persons. They paint Justice as blind to gender and nationality. Its principles are those that would regulate the action of idealized "abstract individuals", hence take no account of differences between men and women and transcend international boundaries. Relativized accounts of Justice not only acknowledge the variety and differences among humankind, but ground principles of Justice in the discourse and traditions of actual communities. Since nearly all of these relegate (varying portions of) women's lives to a 'private' sphere, within which the political virtue of Justice has no place, and see national boundaries as limits of Justice, appeals to actual traditions tend both to endorse institutions that exclude women from the 'public' sphere, where Justice is properly an issue, and to insulate one 'public' sphere from another. Both idealized and relativized accounts of Justice look inadequate from the perspective of those whom they marginalize. Women, in particular poor women, will find that neither approach takes account of the reality of carrying both reproductive and 1 productive tasks, while having relatively little control over the circumstances of one's life. Women's lives are not well conceLved dust as those of idealized individuals. A world of ,such individuals assumes away relations of dependence and interdependence; yet these are central to most lives actually available to women. Nor are womens's lives well conceived solely in terms of traditions that relegate them to a 'private' sphere. The productive contributions and the cognitive and practical independence of actual women are too extensive, evident and economically significant to be eclipsed by ideologies of total domesticity and dependence. The awkward fit of theory to actuality is most vivid for poor women in poor economies. These women may depend on others, but lack the supposed securities of dependence. They are impoverished, but are often providers. They are powerless, yet others who are yet more vulnerable depend on them for 1 protection. Their vulnerability reflects heavy demands as much as slender resources. They may find that they are relegated to and subordinated within a domestic sphere, whose separate and distinctive existence is legitimated not by appeals to justice but by entrenched views of family life and honour. They may also find that this domestic sphere is embedded in an economy that is subordinate to distant and richer economies. They not only raise children in poverty; they raise crops and do ill-paid and insecure work whose rewards fluctuate to the beat of distant economic forces. This second subordination too is legitimated in varied discourses which endorse an internationalized econoirio order but only national regimes of taxation and welfare. A serious account of Justice cannot gloss over the predicaments of impoverished providers in marginalized and developing economies. 2 2. PREVIEW: ABSTRACT PRINCIPLES AND CONTEXT SENSITIVE JUDGEMENT Both idealized and relativized approaches to justice make seemingly legitimate demands. Idealized approaches insist that justice must abstract from the particularities of persons. Blindness to difference is a traditional image of Justice and guarantees impartiality. Yet principles of justice that are supposedly blind to differences of power and resources often seem to endorse practices and policies that suit the privileged. Hence a demand that justice take account of context can seem equally reasonable. Justice, it is argued, needs more than abstract principles: it must guide judgements that take account of actual contexts and predicaments and of the differences among human beings. Relativized principles of justice meet this demand: but since they are rooted in history, tradition or local context, they will endorse traditional sexism or nationalism. Any relativism tends to prejudice the position of the weak, whose weakness is mirrored and partly constituted by their marginalization in received ways of thought and by their subordination and oppression in established orders. Yet idealizing approaches do no better. Where relativist approaches are uncritical of established privilege, idealized approaches are uncritical of privileges from which they abstract. If accounts of justice had to be either idealized or relativized. we would have to choose between demands for abstraction from difference and for sensitivity to difference. If there are other possibilities, an account of justice may be able to meet demands both for abstract principles and for context sensitive judgements. I shall try to sketch a third possibility, which gives both abstraction and sensitivity to context their due 3 -- but only their due. This can be done by meeting the demands for abstraction from and sensitivity to context in two distinct, successive moves. The first move is to argue for abstract principles of universal scope, while rejecting the supposed link between abstraction and positions that not merely abstract but (in a sense to be explained) idealize. Much contemporary moral reasoning. and in particular 'abstract liberalism' (whether *deontological' or utilitarian), handles issues of gender and international justice badly not because it abstracts (e.g from sex, race, nationality), but because it also almost always idealizes specific conceptions of the human agent and of national sovereignty which are often admired and are more (nearly) feasible for men rather than for women and for developed rather than developing societies. However, abstraction itself, without idealization, is the route rather than the obstacle to broad scope and is unobjectionable in principles of justice. The second move answers demands that we take account of the context and particularities of lives and societies. but does not build culturally specific ideals of gender and of national sovereignty into the principles of justice. The second move insists that judgements of justice take account of cert ain differences by applying abstract principles to determinate cases without tacitly reintroducing restricted ideals ( e . g . o f gender and national sovereignty) so relativising principles of justice to accepted beliefs, traditions or practices. Abstract principles can guide context sensitive judgement without lapsing into relativism. 4 3. ABSTRACT JUSTICE AND HUMAN DIFFERENCES: FEMINIST DEBATES. Discussions of gender justice have been structured by disagreements over the extent and import of differences between men and women. For liberals who defend abstract principles of Justice it has been embarassing that the Rights of Man were taken for so long and by so many of their predecessors as the rights of men, and that liberal practice failed for so long to end male 2 privilege. (Socialist feminists suffer analogous embarassments). Starting with Wollstonecraft and J.S. Mill, liberal feminists argued against women's difference. and claimed that women's like rationality entitled them to equal rights. More recent liberal feminists have noted that even when women had equal political and legal rights, their political participation and economic rewards remained less than those of men, and less than those of men whose qualifications and labour force participation women matched. Supposedly gender-neutral and neutralizing institutions, such as democratic political 3 structures and markets, did not eliminate gender differentials. Many have concluded that approximations to political and legal Justice in various domains of life evidently cannot close the ft radical gap between men's and women's paths and prospects. In response some liberal feminists argued that justice demands more thorough equal treatment. For example, it may require forms of affirmative action and reverse discrimination in education and employment, as well as welfare rights to social support for the poor and those with heavy family responsibilities. Some differences are to be acknowledged in principles of Justice. This move has two difficulties. First, many liberals deny that Justice demands compensatory 5 redistribution, especially of positional goods. They think these should be allocated by competitive and meritocratic procedures. This debate is of particular importance in the developed world. The second problem arises even where the goods to be distributed are not positional, and is particularly significant in the Third World. Where resources are scarce, non-positional goods such as basic health care or income support or children's allowances or unemployment insurance may be unfundable out of a slender national tax base. If social justice demands basic welfare provision, justice must reach across boundaries. An account of gender justice would then have to be linked to one of 5 international distributive justice. This liberal debate continues, but its terms have been increasingly questioned by feminists in the last decade, many of whom claim that, despite its aspirations, gender bias is 6 integral to liberal justice. Their suspicions focus on the very abstraction from difference and diversity which has been the hallmark of liberal justice. Some of these 'post-liberal' feminists criticize abstract liberalism by highlighting respects in which particular supposedly gender-neutral theories -overtly assume or endorse gendered accounts of the human subject and of rationality. Many aspects of these critiques are convincing. However, the most fundamental contemporary feminist challenge to abstract liberalism ostensibly impugns reliance on abstraction itself. Gilligan's influential work claims that an emphasis on justice excludes and marginalizes the 'other voice' of ethical thought. 'Abstract liberalism1 simply and unacceptably devalues care and concern for particular others, which are the core of womens' moral life and thought, seeing 7 them as moral immaturity. The voice of justice is 6 intrinsically 'male' in its refusal to grasp the actualities of human difference, in its supposed agnosticism about the good for man, and its resulting disregard of the virtues, and specifically of love and care. On this account the problem is not to secure like treatment for women, but to secure differentiated treatment for all. In locating the distinction between justice and care (and other virtues) in a disagreement over the legitimacy of relying on abstract principles, feminist critics of abstract liberalism often view concern for care as not merely different from but opposed to concern for Justice. They can end up endorsing rather than challenging social and economic structures that marginalize women and confine them to a private sphere. Separatism at the level of ethical theory can march with acceptance of the powers and traditions that be. A stress on caring and relationships to the exclusion of abstract justice may endorse relegation to the nursery and the kitchen, to purdah and to poverty. In rejecting 'abstract liberalism' such feminists converge with traditions that have excluded women from economic and public life. An appeal to 'women's experience', 'women's traditions' and 'women's discourse' does not escape, but rather echoes, ways in which women have been marginalized or oppressed. Those who celebrate the other 'voice' often assume that differences. are taken seriously 8 only when actual differences are endorsed. The disputes that now divide liberal feminists and their contextualist critics ostensibly pose an unwelcome dilemma about gender justice. If we adopt an abstract account of justice, which is blind to differences between people, so to the ways in which women's lives in the developed and in the undeveloped world 7 differ from men's lives, we commit ourselves (it is said) to uniform treatment regardless of difference. But if we acknowledge the ethical importance of human differences. we are likely to endorse traditional social forms that sustain those differences, including those that subordinate and oppress women. 4. ABSTRACT JUSTICE AND NATIONAL DIFFERNCE: COMMUNITARIAN DEBATES This dilemma recurs in certain discussions of international Justice. Abstract liberalism proclaims the Rights of Man. As Burke was quick to complain. this is quite a different matter from proclaiming the traditional rights of Englishmen, or of Frenchmen, or of any coherent group. Abstraction was the price to be paid for ethical discourse that could cross the boundaries of states and nations and have universal appeal; and Burke found the price unacceptable. The internationalist, cosmopolitan commitments that were implicit in the ideals of liberalism have repeatedly been targets of conservative and communitarian criticism. Liberal practice has, however, once again teen quite different. It has not been universalistic, but clearly subordinated to the boundaries and demands of nation states. This is evident in relations between rich and poor states. Like treatment for like cases is partially secured by laws and practices within many democratic states; only a few enthusiasts argue for world government, or think that rights of residence, work and welfare, as well as burdens of taxation, should be global. Such enthusiasm is often dismissed by practical people who hold that a plurality of national Jurisdictions provides the framework(s) within which liberal ideals can be pursued. Liberals may not be generally willing to take differences seriously; but 8 they have taken differences between sovereign states remarkably seriously. Their communitarian critics want to take differences and 9 boundaries seriously in theory as well as in practice. When boundaries are taken wholly seriously. however, international Justice is not Just played down, but wiped off the ethical map. Walzer's work is a good case in point. He holds that the largest sphere of Justice is the political community and that the only issues not internal to such communities are about membership in them and conflicts between them. The issues of membership concern the admission of individual aliens: rights and duties do 10 not go beyond borders. A commitment to community is a commitment to the historical boundaries of political communities, whatever these happen to be and whatever injustices their constitution and their preservation cost. Communitarians cannot easily take any wider view of ethical boundaries since their critique of abstraction is in part a demand for ethical discourse that takes 11 'our' language, 'our' culture and 'our' traditions seriously. Like current debates on gender Justice, discussions of international Justice apparently pose an unwelcome choice. Either we can abstract from the reality of boundaries, and think about principles of Justice that assume an ideal, cosmopolitan world, in which Justice and human rights do not stop at the boundaries of states. Or we can acknowledge the reality of boundaries and construe the principles of Justice as subordinate to those of national sovereignty. Cosmopolitan ideals are evident in the discourse of much of the human rights movement; but some recent liberal theorists have shifted towards the relativism of their 9 communitarian critics, and even view liberal principles of justice as no more than the principles of liberal societies. 12 Rawls in particular now hinges his theory of Justice not on an abstract and idealized construction of an original position but on the actual ideals of citizens of liberal democratic societies. Here we see a surprising and perhaps unstable convergence between abstract liberal theorists and their communitarian critics. 5. ABSTRACTION WITH AND WITHOUT IDEALISATION Debates about gender and international justice are rot merely similar in that each is structured by a confrontation between advocates of abstract principles and of context sensitive Judgements. In each debate the two parties depict these demands as incompatible. However, the reason for the incompatiblity may be that many advocates of abstraction and of sensitivity to context are making other, stronger claims that are indeed incompatible. What these debates term 'abstraction* is often a set of specific, unargued idealizationa of human agency, rationality and life and of the sovereignty and independence of states. And in each debate what is described as attention to actual situations and contexts in judging in fact often extends to building recognition of differnces into fundamental principles— and so amounts to relativism. These conflations are avoidable. Abstraction, taken strictly, is simply a matter of detaching certain claims from others. Abstract reasoning hinges nothing on the satisfaction or non-satisfaction of predicates from which it abstracts. All uses of language must abstract more or less: the most detailed describing cannot dent the indeterminacy of language. Indeed it isn't obvious that there is 10 anything to object to in very abstract principles of justice. Highly abstract ways of reasoning are often admired (mathematics, physics), and frequently well paid (accountancy, law). What is different about abstract ethical reasoning? When we look at objections to 'abstract' ethical principles and reasoning in detail it appears that they are often objections not to detachment from certain predicates. but to the inclusion of predicates that are false of the objects of the domains to which a theory is then applied. Reasoning that abstracts from some predicate makes claims that do not hinge on the objects to which the reasoning is applied satsifying that predicate. Reasoning that idealizes makes claims that hinge on the objects to which it is applied satisfying certain predicates. Where those predicates are unsatisfied the reasoning simply does not apply. The principles and theories of Justice to which the critics of 'abstract liberalism' object are indeed abstract. They take no account of many features of agents and societies. However, these principles and theories not only abstract but idealize. They assume. for example. accounts of rational choice whose claims about information, coherence, capacities to calculate and the like are not merely not satisfied by some deficient or backward agents, but are actually satisfied by no human agents (perhaps they are approximated, or at least admired, in restricted shopping and gambling contexts!). They also assume idealized accounts of the mutual independence of persons and their opportunities to pursue their individual 'conceptions of the good', and of the sovereignty and independence of states, that are false of all human beings and all states. Such idealizations no doubt have theoretical advantages: above all they allow us to construct models that can readily be 11 manipulated. However, they fail to apply to most, if not all, practical problems of human choice and foreign policy. If idealized descriptions are not simply abstracted from descriptions that are true of actual agents, they are not innocuous ways of extending the scope of reasoning. Each idealization posits an 'enhanced' version of the objects of the domain to which the model is applied. Idealizations may privilege certain sorts of human agent and life and certain sorts of society by covertly presenting (enhanced versions of) their specific characteristics as true of all human action and life. In this way covert gender chauvinism and an exaggerated view of state sovereignty can be combined with liberal principles. Idealization masquerading as abstraction yields theories that appear to apply widely, but which covertly exclude those who don't match a certain ideal, or match it less well that others. Those who are excluded are then seen as defective or inadequate. A reconsideration of debates about gender and international justice shows that the feminist and communitarian critics of liberal Justice could legitimately attack spurious idealizations without impugning abstraction that eschews idealization. 6. GENDER AND IDEALISED AGENTS Liberal discussions of justice ostensibly hinge nothing on gender differences. They apply to individuals, considered in abstraction from specific identities, commitments and circumstances. Recent critics insist that liberal theories of justice are far from being as gender blind as their advocates claim. An instructive example is Rawls' A. Theory of Justice. Rawls was particularly concerned t^m* to avoid an extravagant view of human agents. His principles of justice are those that would 12 be chosen by agents in an 'original position' in which they know less rather than more_ than actual human agents. He conceives his work as carrying the social contract tradition to "a higher level of abstraction". In particular, agents in the original position do not know their social and economic position, their natural 13 assets or their conceptions of the good. The original position operatlonalizes the image of justice as blind to difference. However, Rawls has at a certain point to introduce grounds for those in the original position to care about their successors. He suggests that we may think of them as heads or at others times as representatives of families, "as being so to 114 speak deputies for an everlasting moral agent or institution" and that some form of family would be dust. In doing so he preempts the question of intra-familial Justice. He preempts the question not by crude insistence that heads of families must be men, but by taking it as read that there is some Just form of family which allows the interests of some to be Justly represented by others. The shift from individuals to heads of families as agents of construction is not an innocent abstraction: it assumes a family structure which secures identity of interests between distinct individuals. It takes for granted 15 that there is some Just 'sexual contract', that Justice can presuppose a legitimate separation of 'private' from 'public' domains. This is idealization indeed: it buries the question of gender Justice rather than resolving it. Rawls' text leaves it surprisingly obscure whether some (women?) are to be relegated to a 'private' sphere and represented by others (men?) in the construction of Justice, whether both 'public' and 'private' 13 realms are to be shared by all on equal terms or whether some 16 (women?) alone are to carry the burdens of both spheres. The more radical feminist critique of abstract liberalism refuses not merely the supressed gendering of the subject which Pateman and Okin detect in classical and contemporary liberal writers. but abstraction itself. In advocating an ethic of care these critics come close both to traditional misogynist positions and to ethical relativism. When the 'voices'of justice and of care are presented as alternatives between which we must choose, each is viewed as a complete approach to moral issues. However, the two in fact focus on different aspects of life. Justice is concerned with institutions, care and other virtues with character. which is vital in unmediated relationships with particular others (and perhaps also important in ediated relationships). The central difference between the 'voices' of justice and of care is not that they demand that we reason in different ways. Justice requires judgements about cases as well as abstract principles; care is principled as well as responsive to differences. Justice matters for impoverished providers because their predicament is one of institutionally structured poverty which cannot be banished by idealizing an ethic of care and insisting on its place in face to face relationships. 7. IDEALIZED BOUNDARIES A comparable slide from unavoidable abstraction to suspect idealization can be found in discussions of international justice. Discussions of global economic and political issues often take it for granted that the principal actors are states. Traditionally the main divide in these discussions has been between realists, who contend that states, although agents, are 14 exempt from moral obligations and criticism, and idealists who insist that states are not merely agents but accountable agents 17 who must meet the demands of justice. However, in discussions of distributive justice, the salient issue has not been the conflict between idealists and realists, but their agreement that state boundaries define the main actors in international affairs. These shared terms of debate endorse an exaggerated. idealized view of the agency and mutual independence of sovereign states, which is increasingly criticized as obsolete. The common ground on which realists and idealists traditionally debated international relations is being eroded as other actors, including international agencies, regional associations and above all transnational corporations, play a 18 more and more significant role in world affairs. A world that is partitioned into discrete and mutually impervious sovereign states is not an abstraction from our world, but an idealized version of it, or perhaps an idealized version of what it once was. Realists as well as idealists idealize the sovereignty of states. Idealized conceptions both of state sovereignty and of state boundaries limit discussions of international distributive Justice. Although long subject to theoretical questioning from advocates of human rights, who deny that states can be sovereign in determining the fates of individuals, many liberals are coy about criticising rights violations beyond boundaries. They limit criticism to violations of liberty rights. and offer little acount of the agency or responsibilities of institutions; they find it hard to see how justice could require that state boundaries be breached to reduce poverty that lies beyond them. 15 We still speak of international rather than of transnational Justice. Even those liberals who defend welfare rights are often concerned with welfare in one (rich) country. It is common to classify economic development of poorer regions as optional 'aid', not obligatory Justice. Those who have tried to argue for global welfare rights within a liberal framework have to show who bears the obligations that correspond to these rights, and this 19 has proved an uphill task. Meanwhile liberals, like communitarians, confine Justice within national boundaries. Liberals do so self-consciously and provisionally; communitarians on priniciple and unapologetically; others tacitly and without discussion. 8. ABSTRACTION WITHOUT IDEALIZATION The only way to find theories that have wide scope is to abstract from the particularities of agents; but when abstraction is displaced by idealization we are not led to theories with wide scope, but to theories that apply only to idealized agents. This suggests that if we are interested in international or in gender Justice we should resist the temptation to rely on idealizing models of human agency or national sovereignty. we should instead consider what sort of theory of Justice we would have if we abstract but refuse to idealize any one conception of rationality or independence, and so avoid marginalizing or excluding those who don't live up to specific ideals of rationality or of independence from others. Abstraction without idealization may allow us to consider a wide range of human agents and Institutional arrangments without hingeing anything on the specific features of agents' traditions, ideologies .and capacities to act. If we could do this we might avoid idealized 16 accounts of agency and sovereignty without following feminist and communitarian critics of abstract liberalism into relativism. Recent discussions may simply have been mistaken in treating appeals to idealized and to relativized standards of rationality and agency as the only options. There are other possibilities. We do not have to hinge liberal arguments for rights or for the limits of government power either on the hypothetical consent of those who meet some ideal standard of rationality and mutual independence, or on the actual acceptance of an outlook and its categories that relativizes consent to an established order. We could instead begin simply by abstracting from existing social orders. We could consider what principles of action must be adopted by agents who are numerous, diverse and neither ideally rational nor ideally independent of one another, and yet avoid specific assumptions about these agents. We can bracket both idealizations and the status QUO. The issue then becomes: how powerful and convincing an account of Justice can we offer if we appeal neither to fictions of ideal rationality and independence nor to the contingencies of actual agents and institutions? What happens if we abstract without idealizing? 9. PLURALITY AND JUSTICE: WHO COUNTS? Let us begin with the thought of a plurality of potentially interacting and diverse agents. This rules out two cases. First, it rules out the case where justice is not a problem because there is no plurality, or no genuine plurality, of agents, hence no potential for conflict between agents. (The action of agents in such a degenerate plurality might be automatically or necessarily coordinated, e.g. by instinct or by a preestablished harmony) Second, it rules out hingeing an 17 account of justice on an assumed, contingent and determinate limit to the diversity of its members. which provides a common ground between them and permits a contingent, socially guaranteed convergence and coordination. The two cases that are ruled out are once again those which would base principles of justice on an assumed ideal convergence or an assumed actual historical or social convergence. What does justice require of such a plurality? At least we can claim that their most basic principles must be ones that could be adopted by all. If they were not, at least some agemts would have to be excluded from the plurality for whom the principles can hold, whose boundaries would have to be drawn more narrowly. Such a redrawing of boundaries is, of course, the very move often used to exclude women and foreigners, let alone foreign women, from the domain of justice. Those who exclude simply refuse to count certain others as members of a plurality of potentially interacting agents. The universalist aspirations of an account of justice which hinges on the sharability of principles can easily be derailed by excluding some from the domain of Justice without argument. So it is important to see the move for what it is. This can best be done by asking who makes the move. The move is not made by idealized genderless theorists who live outside state and society. It is made by people who generally expect women to interact with them, to follow language and reason, to understand and take part in elaborate traditions and institutions, perhaps even to love, honour and obey. It is made by people who expect ordinary processes of translation, 18 trade and negotiation to work with foreigners. To deny the agency of others with whom we interact in complex ways reeks of bad faith. Bad faith can be avoided only by counting as members of the plurality for whom principles of justice are to hold anybody i. with whom interaction is to be undrtaken or held possible. The question then becomes: are there any principles which must be adopted by all members of a plurality of potentially interacting agents? We cannot simply stipulate that such principles are irrelevant for interactions with certain others on whose (no doubt imperfect) capacities to reason and (no doubt limited) abilities to act independently we know we depend. If women were all transported to Betelgeuse, and so beyond all interaction with the remnant men on Earth. neither men nor women would have to see the other as falling within the domain of justice. Less fancifully, since the ancient inhabitants of the Andes and their contemporaries in Anglo-Saxon England could not and did not interact, neither would have acted in bad faith if they excluded the other from the domain of justice. Neither of them could practice either justice or injustice to the other. Things are different for the actual men and women who inhabit the earth now: the potential for interaction cannot be assumed away, and others cannot be arbitrarily excluded from the domain of justice. We rely on global economic and political processes, so cannot consistently insist that justice (conveniently for the developed world) stops at state frontiers, any more than we can rely on women's rationality and their productive contribution and then argue that justice (conveniently for some men) stops at the edge of a supposed 'private' sphere, whose existence and demarcation is in fact presupposed in defining a 'public' sphere. 19 10. PLURALITY AND JUSTICE: WHAT PRINCIPLES? Justice is then in the first place a matter of keeping to principles that can be adopted by any plurality of potentially interacting beings. But if we eschew both idealization and relativism, and rely on mere abstraction, will we have strong enough premisses to identify those principles? Does a universalizability test cut any ice? Granted that universalizability is not uniformity (as some critics of abstract liberalism suppose), is it not too weak a demand to ground an acount of justice? In particular, will not any internally coherent principle for Individual action be a universallzable 20 principle? We have, however, to remember that we are considering the case of a plurality of potentially interacting beings, that is of beings who share a world. Any principle of action that is adopted by all members of such pluralities alters the world that they share and becomes a background condition of their action. This is why certain principles of action which can coherently be held by one agent cannot be coherently proposed as principles for all. Examples of non-universalizable principles can illustrate the point. A principle of deception, which undermines trust, would, if universally adopted, make all trusting, hence all projects of deception, incoherent. Selective deception is on the cards: universal deception is impossible. Since nobody who hopes to deceive can coherently will that a principle of deception be fundamental to the practice of any plurality, Justice requires that it be rejected. Equally, a policy of coercion, which seeks to destroy or undercut others' agency and independence, cannot (without Incoherence) be universally prescribed by one who seeks to coerce, since its universal 20 adoption puts any coercer's agency and plans to coerce at risk. Those who are victims of coercion cannot (while victims) also act 21 on the principles on which their coercers act. Equally, a principle of violence which damages the agency of some others cannot be universally acted on. Put quite generally, nobody whose own principles of action hinge on victimising some, so on destroying, paralysing or undercutting their capacities for action can be committed to those same principles holding 22 universally. To Keep matters under control let us imagine only that Justice demands (at least) that action and institutions not be based on principles of deception and victimization. (There may be other principles of Justice) Still we are far from showing just what justice demands, since we do not Know what refusing to deceive or to coerce may demand in specific circumstances. These guidelines are highly indeterminate. We seem to have paid the classic price of abstraction. Highly abstract principles do not tell us what to do in a specific context. However abstract principles are only part of practical, or specifically of ethical. reasoning. Principles never determine their own applications; even the culturally specific principles that relativists favour do not determine their own applications. All practical reasoning requires judgement and deliberation by which principles are applied to particular cases. An account of gender and international justice is no exception. We need in particular to be able to judge what specific institutions and action are needed if poor women in poor economies are be accorded justice. 21 11. PLURALITY AND JUSTICE: DELIBERATION WITHOUT RELATIVISM Two background issues must be dealt with summarily before considering moves from abstract basic principles to determinate Judgements. First, we have no reason to expet that principles of Justice will provide any algorithm of rational choice. Nor do we need any algorithm for principles to be important. Even principles that provide only a set of side constraints on action may make exigent demands. Second, we have no reason to think that principles of Justice are relevant only to the action of individuals. A full account of the agency of institutions would be a complex matter. I shall not go into it here, but will assume that it can be given and that institutions and practices, like individuals, must meet the demands of Justice. These moves, however, are preliminary to the main task of giving a more determinate account of what may be required if principles of deception or victimization are rejected. How, for example, can we Judge whether specific types of family or economic activity are based on deception or victimize some? Are all forms of hierarchy and subordination coercive? If not, how do we discern the boundaries of deceit and coercion in actual contexts? It is not hard to see that certain categories of individual action--e.g. fraud or wife burning or battering-- deceive or victimize, but other cases of deception and coercion by individuals are hard to adjudicate. It is may also hard to Judge whether social traditions that isolate or exclude women, or economic and familial arrangments that ensure their acute economic vulnerability, amount to modes of deceit and coercion. In this paper the task cannot be to reach determinate Judgements about particular cases, but only to see whether 22 reasoned moves from very abstract principles towards more specific principles. whose relevance and application to particular cases may be easier to assess, may be possible. It will not be enough to lean on the received criteria by which 'our' tradition or nation picks out ethically significant 'cases' or 'options' for approaching them. We beg questions if we assume that categories of thought that have been hospitable to male dominance and to imperialism can be decisive for discerning or judging Justice to those whose problems have been marginalized and whose agency and capacities have been formed, perhaps deformed, by unjust institutions. We cannot rely uncritically on the categories of established discourse, including the discourse of social scientists and of the 'helping' professions, to pick out the sigificant problems. These categories are themselves 23 matters for ethical concern and criticism. We have, after all, no more reason to trust relativized discussions of justice, gender or boundaries than to trust idealized approaches unequivocally. Those discussions are no more free of theory and ideology than are idealized discussions of justice. Their ways of individuating typical problem cases may be familiar: but familiarity may mask contentious and unjust delimitations. If the received views of a society or tradition are taken as defining the domain of problems to which abstract principles of justice are applied. unvindicated ideals will be introduced and privileged, just as they are in idealized approaches to justice. Some confirmation of the ways in which received descriptions of social relations reflect larger and disputed ideals is suggestive. Consider, for example, how issues of gender can be passed over as if invisible. We often find an enormous amount of 23 shifting around in the choice of basic units of social analysis. In the shifts between descriptions that focus on individuals, wage-earners and heads of families, there is enough flexibility for the blunt facts of economic and other subordination of women to be veiled. Women's low wastes can seem unworrying if they are wives for whom others provide; their dependence on husbands and fathers can seem acceptable if they are after all waste-earning individuals, so not invidiously dependent. Reproductive labour 27 may (with convenient ambiguity?) be thought of as priceless. Wage-earning women's low pay can be seen as fitting their low skills and vindicating their domestic subordination to wage- earning men, who as 'heads of families' are entitled to discretionary expenditure and leisure which wage-earning women must do without because they (unlike men!) have family commitments. The gloomy evidence of social structures and habits of thought that classify women's contributions as less valuable even when more onerous or more skilled are evident enough. We continually find ourselves "thinking about men as individuals who 28 direct households and about women as family members". There are equally serious reasons to mistrust the move from abstract principles to determinate Judgements in discussions of individual motivation. These too are shaped by received views, and in milieux which are strongly individualist are easily diverted into attempts to pin blame for injustices on individuals. Women, after all, commonly acquiesce in their social and economic subordination. Are they then to be blamed for servility? Or are men to be blamed for oppressing or 26 exploiting women? Or do these individualist approaches to assigning blame lead no further than the higher bickering? It can seem that we have reasons to mistrust not only relativist 24 approaches to sender Justice but even the attempt to apply abstract, non-idealized principles of Justice. But we do not inhabit an ideal world. Idealized conceptions of Justice simply do not apply to International relations, social relations or individual acts in a world in which states, men and women always lack the capacities and the opportunities of idealized agents. States are not really sovereign; even superpowers have limited powers; and men and women are always more or less vulnerable, ignorant, insecure, lacking in confidence or means to challenge or oppose the status quo. In a world of agents with finite capacities and opportunities, poor women in poor economies differ not in kind but in degree in their dependence on others and in others' demands on them. 12. JUST DELIBERATION IN A WORLD OF VULNERABLE AGENTS If we are to apply principles of Justice that are neither idealized, nor merely relative to actual societies, to vulnerable lives and their predicaments we must see how to move towards determinate Judgements about actual cases. The principles of Justice for which I have argued take us in this direction because they focus neither on the arrangements to which ideally rational and mutually independent beings would consent, nor on the arrangements to which others in possibly oppressive situations do consent. Rather they ask which arrangements a plurality of interacting agents with finite capacities, could, consent to. I have suggested, provisionally, that this non-idealizing construction identifies the rejection of deception, coercion and other ways of victimising others as principles of Justice. But principles are not enough. Non-idealizing abstraction 25 avoids some problems. but not others. If we are to move from abstract principles to determinate judgements we need to operationalize the idea of avoiding acting on unsharable principles, without subordinating it to the categories and views of the status quo. One reasonable way of doing so might be to ask to what extent the variable aspects of any arrangements that structure vulnerable lives, are ones that could have. been refused OX. renegotiated by_ those whom they actually constrain. If those affected by a given set of arrangments that could in prinicple be changed can in fact refuse or renegotiate them, their consent is no mere formality, but genuine, legitimating consent. If they could not but 'accept' those institutions, their 'consent' will not legitimate. The point of this way of operationalizing the notion of possible consent is that it neither ascribes ideal reasoning capacities and ideal independence from others to agents. nor hinges legitimation on an actual 'consent' that may reflect injustice. On this account justice requires that institutions. like acts, allow those on the receiving end. even if frail and dependent, to refuse or renegotiate any variable aspects of the roles and tasks assigned to them. Dissent becomes harder when capacities to act are Less developed and more vulnerable, and when opportunities for independent action are restricted. Capacities to act are constrained both by lack of abilities and by commitments to others. Institutional arrangements can disable agency both by limiting capacities to reason and act independently and by increasing the demands to meet the needs and satisfy the desires of others. Apparent consent to such arrangements does not show that they are just. Whenever 'consent' reflects lack of capacity or opportunity to do anything but 'consent', it does not 26 legitimate. Thinking in this way about Justice we can see that it demands more not less. to be just to the vulnerable. The vulnerable are much easier to deceive and to victimize than the strong: their 'consent' is all too easily elicited. If we are to Judge proposals for action by seeing whether they involve serious deception or victimization (coercion or violence). more will be demanded when others are vulnerable than when they are 27 secure. and most when they are most vulnerable. By contrast both idealized and relativized accounts of Justice tend to conceal the fact that Justice to the weak demands more than Justice to the strong. Idealized accounts of Justice tend to ignore vulnerability and relativized accounts to legitimate it. 13. ACHIEVING JUSTICE FOR IMPOVERISHED PROVIDERS The lives of poor women in poor economies illustrate these points well. Consider, for example, daily commercial transactions and practices. Their Justice, it is usually said, lies in the fact that arrangements are mutually agreed. But where there are great disparities of knowledge and vulnerability between agents. the 'agreement' of the weak may be spurious. They may have been duped by offers they did not understand or overwhelmed by 'offers' they dared not refuse. Within national Jurisdictions these facts are well recognized, and commercial practice is regulated to prevent pressure and fraud. Contracts can be voided for fraud: there are 'truth in lending' provisions; debt and bankruptcy will not lead to starvation: those with dependents can rely on a safety net of welfare rights. International economic transactions take place in a far less regulated space, yet link agents with far greater disparities in 27 power and resources. The weak can suffer both from particular others who take advantage of their ignorance and vulnerability, and because nothing informs them about or shields them from the intended or unintended consequences either of distant or of local economic forces. The poor, and above all those who are impoverished providers, cannot refuse or renegotiate their role in economic structures or transactions which hurt them, even when these structures and transactions could in prinicple be changed. They are vulnerable not only to low wages, low standards of industrial safety, endemic debt and disadvantageous dependence on 28 those who provide credit, but also to disadvantageous patterns of entitlement within the family. For example, debtors who need further loans for survival cannot make much fuss about 23 the terms creditors offer for purchasing their crops. In many societies the position of certain women-- daughters-in-law, for example, and younger girls--is acutely vulnerable. Vulnerable agents on whom others depend are at the mercy both of market forces and of more powerful kin. Idealized pictures of Justice have tended to overlook the import of economic power: by idealizing the capacities and the mutual independence of those involved in market transactions they obscure why the weak may be unable to dissent from arrangments proposed by the strong. They also tend to distinguish sharply between intended and unintended consequences, and to view the latter as unavoidable 'forces'. Yet these forces are themselves the outcome of institutional arrangements and could be changed or modified, as they have been within many jurisdictions. The problem of shielding the weak from these forces is nothing to do with 'natural' processes, and everything to do with the weakness of the voices that call for change. This is hardly surprising. 28 Market institutions magnify the security and so the voices of the haves. Formal democracy provides only slender and partial redress for the weak, and is often lacking. Typical family structures also illustrate the gulf between ideally Independent aeents (whom market structures might suit) and actual powerlessness. These structures often draw a boundary between 'public' and 'private' domains, assign women (wives and daughters) to the 'private' domain and leave them with slender control of resources, but heavy commitments to meet others' needs. They may lack adequate economic entitlements, effective enfranchisement or access to sources of information or debate by which to check or challenge the proposals and plans of more powerful family mmebers. Women in this predicament lack security, and must meet the demands of others (often fathers and husbands) who dominate them. Family structures can enable, even impose, forms of deception and domination. Where women are isolated, secluded. barred from education or wage earning. or have access to information only via the filter of more powerful family members, their judgement is weakened, and their independence stunted. Often this vulnerability may be shielded by matching concern and restraint; often it will not. A rhetoric of familial concern and protective paternalism can easily camouflage callous lack of concern and legitimate deceptive acts and practices. Similar points can be made about victimization. A principle of refusing coercion, for example, basically demands that action not undercut others' agency. If agents were all ideally independent of one another. they might find little difficulty in dissenting from many forms of attempted domination. However, 29 + 30 family structures always limit independence, and usually limit women's independence more. A woman who has no adequate entitlements of her own and insecure rights to a share in family property or income, will not always be coerced, but is always 29 vulnerable to coercion. When her independence is also restricted by family responsibilities she will be even easier to coerce. In these circumstance ostensible consent reveals little; it certainly does not legitimate forms of domination and subordination. Relations of dependence are not always or overtly coercive; but they provide structures of subordination within which it is all too easy to silence or trivialize the articulation of dissent. To guarantee that action is not based on principles which others cannot share, it is necessary to ensure that proposals that affect others are ones from which they. can dissent. Institutionalized dependence tends to make dissent hard or impossible. Those who cannot secure economic independence or who cannot rely on others to take a share in caring for genuine dependents (children,the elderly) cannot easily say 'no' or set their own terms. They must go along with the proposals of the more powerful. Genuine. legitimating consent is. undermined by the very Institutions which most readily secure an appearance of consent. The more relations with others are ones of structured dependence, the more the weak have to depend on trusting that the (relatively) strong will not exercise the advantages which proximity and relations of dependence give them. When the strong reliably show this restraint there may in fact be no injustice within relationships which institutionalize dependence. However, institutions that rely too heavily on the self-restraint of the stronger cannot reliably avoid injustice. Whether the proposals 31 of the strong are economic or sexual, whether they rely on the ignorance and isolation of the weak to deceive them, on their diminished opportunities for independent action, or on the habits of deference and appeasement which become second nature for the weak, they ride on unjust social practices. The weak risk recurrent Injustice unless Institutions are. structured to. secure thS option of refusal or renegotiation of variable arrangements for those whose capacities and. opportunities are limited. A woman who has no entitlements of her own lives at the discretion of other family members who have them, so is likely to have to go along even with proposals she greatly dislikes or Judges imprudent. If she were an ideally independent agent, or even had the ordinary independence and opportunities of those who have entitlements adequate for themselves and their dependents, she could risk dissent from or at least renegotiate variable aspects of proposals that are put by those who control her means of life. Being powerless and vulnerable she cannot readily do either. Hence any consent that she offers is compromised and does not legitimate others' proposals. Just as we would find it absurd to hinge legitimating consent to medical treatment on procedures geared to the cognitive capacities and Independence of a notional 'ideal rational patient', so we should find it absurd to hinge legitimating consent to others' plans on the cognitive capacities and independence of a notional ideal rational impoverished and dependent provider for others. This is not to say that impoverished providers are irrational or wholly dependent or cannot consent. However, it is a matter of taking seriously the ways in which their capacities and their opportunities for action constrain their possibilities 32 tho.se for refusal and negotiation. If they are to be treated with justice, others who interact with them must not rely on these reduced capacities and opportunities to impose their will. Those who do so rely on unjust institutional structures that enable deceit, coercion and forms of victimization. In applying abstract, non-idealizing principles we have to take account not indeed of the actual beliefs, ideals or categories of others, which may reflect unjust traditions, but of others' actual capacities and opportunities to act-- and their incapacities and lack of opportunities. This move does net lead back to relativism: no principle is endorsed because it is actually accepted. Put in general terms we can use modal notions to identify principles, but indicative ones to apply them. The principles of justice can be determined for any possible plurality: for they demand only the rejection of principles that cannot be shared by all members of a plurality. Judgements of the justice of actual situations are regulated but not entailed by these principles. The most significant features of actual situations that must be taken into account in judgements of justice are the security or vulnerability that allow actual others to dissent from and to seek change in variable aspects of the arrangements which structure their lives. 33 FOOTNOTES Z would particularly lika to thank Deborah Fitzmeuriee. James Griffin, Barbara Harriss, Martha Nussbaum and Sara Ruddick for help with various problema that aroae in writing; thia paper. 1. of. Ruddiek, (1980). Her account of women's predicament stressas that it raflecta heavy demands as much as meagre reaources. To be preferred. I think, because it doea not take for granted that the lack of reaourcea la significant because "public" while the pross of others' demanda is leaa so because merely "private". 2. Okln. (1979)1 Chervet, (1982); Pateman. (1988); Jaggar. (1983) 3. Scott, (1986). 4. The differences run the gamut of aocial indicators. Moat dramatically in soma Third World countries women and girls do worse on a constellation of very basic social lndieatorats: they die earlier, have worse health, eat less than other family members. earn leaa and go to school less. See Sen.(1987)( Harriss. (1988) and (forthcoming). 5. The problem la not merely one of reaourcea. Where funds have been adequate for publicly funded welfare provision, this too has been inadequate to eliminate the differences between the economic and political prospects of men and of women. For example, many women in the socialist countries find that they have secured greater equality in productive labour with no reduction in reproductive tasks. This is a reason for doubting that arguments establishing welfare rights—e.g. a right to food— take a broad enough view of disparities between men's and women's prospects. 33 a . Footnotes/ Justice Gender Boundaries 6. E.g. Patemen, (1968); Okin. (1987). 7. Gilligan, (1982)t Kittay and Meyers. (1987)I Lloyd. (1984)t MacMillan. (1982): Ruddick. (1987): Noddings. (1984): Chodorow. (1978). 8. This should not surprise us: "women's experience", as many feminists urge In other contexts. is not unmediateds it mirrors the traditional relegation of women to a "private" sphere. 9. Such approaches can be found in Walzer. (1983)} Sandal. (1982): MacIntyre. (1981) and (1984): Williams (1985) and. perhaps moat surprisingly. Rawls, (1985). For some discussion of the implications of these works for international justice see O'Neill (1988b). 10. Walzer acknowledges that this means that he can "only begin to address the problems raisad by mass poverty in many parts of the globe"i (1983) p.30. Critics may think that his approach in fact preempts answers to questions of global justice. 11. Communitarians can, however, take lesser loyalties seriouslyt where a state is divided into distinct national and ethical communities. those distinct traditions may in fact be the widest boundaries within which issues of Justice can be debated and determined. They could argue for secession from a multinational state: but they cannot say anything about what goes on beyond the boundaries of "our" community. of. Walzer, (1983) p. 319. 12. Rawls, (1985). 13. Rawls, (1970), pp. 11-12. 14. Rawls, (1970) p. 128 15. of. Pateman. (1988): Nioholaon, (1987). 16. See Okin, (1987). pp. 46-7. She considers whether the original position abstracts from knowledge of one's sex. Even if she is right in thinking that Rawls relies on a covertly gendered 34 Footnotes/ Justice Gender Boundaries account of the subject, this idaalisation may hava little affact on his theory of Juatice if the thought axparlmant of the original position has so ralantlassly auprassad differanca that the auppoaad plurality of voices is a fiction. In that case we should read the work as taking an idealised rather than a merely abatrect view of rational choice from the vary start, and as appealing to a aingle ideally informed and dlapassionate figure as thegenerator of the principles of Justice. 17. See Baits, (1979) for an account of dabatea between realists and idealists. 18. Kechana and Nye. (1970): Lupar-Foy (1988). 19. See Shue (1980): (1984)s Alston and Tomasavski (1984): Brown and Shue (1977): Gewirth (198 ): Lupar-Foy (1988): O'Neill (1986). 20. This is the hoary problem of formalism in Kantian ethics. For recant dlaouaaiona of aspacta of the problem see Bittner, (1971) Hoffe. (1977): O'Neill. (1985a) and (1985b) 21. It doea not follow that every coercive act la unjust--some coercion, e.g. the use of sanctions to enforce law--may be the condition of any reliable apace for uncoerced action. In such cases the appropriate exprassion of an underlying principle of rejecting coercion is, surprisingly, and crucially for political argument, one that, taken out of context, might axpress an underlying principle of coarcion. 22. I have put these matters briefly. For more extended treatment see the rafarances for 20. and O'Neill (1988a). 23. Ecelman. (1984) 24. Nicholson. (1987) 25. Scott (1986): Sen. (1987)1 Stiehm. (1983). 35 Footnotes/ Justice Gender Boundaries 26. Hill. (1979): San (1987)t Pfaffar (1985)l Postow (1978-9). 27. I focus here on the obligations of the strong rather than the rights of the waak. Thia la not to deny that agitation and resistance by the wask can halp remind and persuade the strong of their obligations and maka it more difficult for them to rapudlata tham. Howaver, to foous primarily on rights falsifies tha predicament of the wask. who ape in no poaition to ensure that others meat their obligations. 28. Shue. (1984): Harries (1987) and forthcoming. 29. Sea Sen (1987) for a wider account of entitlements. 36 REFERENCES ALSTON, P. (1984) 'International Law and the Human Right to Food' in P. Alston and K. Tomasevski, (eds. ) The. Right to Food Nijhoff, Dordrecht. ALSTON P. and TOMASEVSKI, Nijhoff, Dordrecht. K. (eds.) (1981) The Right to Food. BEITZ, CHARLES (1979) Political Theory and International Relations. Princeton University Press, Princeton, N.J.. BITTNER, RUDIGER (1971) "Maximen" in G. Funke (ed.), Akten des 1. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses. De Gruyter, Berlin. BROWN, PETER and SHUE, HENRY (eds.) (1977) Food Policy: The Responsibility of. the United States in Life and. Death Choices. Free Press, New York. CHARVET, JOHN (1982).Feminism. Dent and Sons, London. CHODOROW, NANCY (1978) The Reproduction of of California Press, Berkeley, California. University EDELMAN, MURRAY (1981) "The Political Language of the Helping Professions" Michael J. Shapiro, (ed.). Language and Politics. N.Y.U. Press, New York. GILLIGAN, CAROL (1982) In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women's Dependence. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts. HARRISS, BARBARA (1987) "Merchants and Markets of Grain in South Asia" in Peasants and. Peasant Societies. (ed.) Teodor Shanin, Blackwell, Oxford. ,1988) South Asia. Female Mortality and Health Care in Papers. Queen Elizabeth House, Oxford. (forthcoming) 'Intrafamily Distribution of Hunger in South Asia', in Dreze J. and Sen, A.K., (eds.), Hunger: Economics and. Policy. Clarendon Press, Oxford. HILL. THOMAS (1973) "Servility and Self Respect", Monist HOFFE, OTFRIED (1977) "Kants kategorischer Imperativ als Kriterium des Sittlichen", Zeltschrift for Philosophiche he Forschung. 31. 351-81. HOFFMAN, STANLEY (1981) Duties. Beyond Borders: on the Limits and Possibilities of. Ethical International Politics, Syracuse University Press, Syracuse, New York. JAGGAR. ALISON M. (1983) Feminist Pontics and Human Nature.. Harvester Press, Brighton. 37 KEOHANE. ROBERT O. AND NYE, JOSEPH S. (eds.) (1970) Transnational Relations and World Politics. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts. KITTAY. EVA FEDERS and MEYERS. DIANE T. (eds.) (1987) women. and Moral Theory. Rowman and Llttlefield, New York. LLOYD, GENVIEVE (1984) The Man of Reason; "Male" and. "Female" in Western Philosophy. Methuen LUPER-FOY, STEPHEN (ed.) (1988) Problems of International Justice. Westview Press, Boulder and London. MACINTYRE. ALASDAIR (1981) After Virtue. Duckworth. London. (1984) ia Patriotism a Virtue?. Philosophy Department, University of Kansas, Lawrence. MACMILLAN, CAROL (1982) Women. Reason and. Nature. Blackwell, Oxford. NICHOLSON, LINDA (1987) 'Feminism and Marx: Integrating Kinship with the Economic' in Seyla Benhabib and Drucilla Cornell, (eds.). Feminism as Critique. Polity Press, Cambridge. NODDINGS NELL (1984) Caring. University of California Press, Berkeley, California. OKIN. SUSAN MILLER (1979) Women in Political Thought. Princeton University Press,Princeton, New Jersey. (1987) "Justice and Gender", Philosophy .and Public Affairs. 16, 1987. 12-72. O'NEILL. ONORA (1986) Faces of Hunger! an Essay on Poverty Justice and Development. George Allen and Unwin, London. (1985a) "Consistency in Action" in Nelson Potter and Mark Timmons, (eds.). Morality and. Universality; Essays in Ethical Universalizability. Reidel, Dordrecht, 159-86 (1985b) "Between Consenting Adults", Philosophy and Public Affairs, 14, 253-77 (1988a) "Children's Rights and Children's Lives", Ethics. 98, 445-463. (1988b) " E t h i c a l R e a s o n i n g and I d e o l o g i c a l P l u r a l i s m " , E t h i c s . 9 8 . 7 0 5 - 7 2 2 . PATEMAN, CAROLE, (1988) The Sexual Contract. Polity Press, Cambridge. PFEFFER. RAYMOND (1985) The Responsibility of Men for the Oppression of w o m a n . Journal of_ Applied Philosophy. 2. 217-229. POSTOW, B.C. (1978-9) 'Economic Dependence and Self-respect', The Philosophical forum, x, 181-201. 38 RAWLS, JOHN (1970) A Theory of_ Justice. Harvard University Press. Cambridge. Massachusetts. (1985) "Justice as Fairness: Political not Metaphysical". Philosophy, and. Public Affairs., 14 223-251. RUDD1CK. SARA (1980) "Maternal Thinking", Feminist Studies. 6, (1987) "Remarks on the Sexual Politics of Reason" in Eva Feders Kittay and Diane T. Meyers, (eds. ) Women And. Moral Theory. Rowman and Littlefield, N.Y. SANDEL, MICHAEL (1982) Liberalism and the Limits of Justice. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. SCOTT, ALISON MACEWEN (1986) in Rosemary Crompton and Michael Mann, (eds.), "Industrialization, Gender Segregation and Stratification Theory", in Gender .and Stratification. Polity Press, Cambridge. SEN, AMARTYA K. (1981) Poverty and Famines; An Essay on Entitlement and Deprivation. Clarendon Press. Oxford. (1987) Gender and Cooperative Conflicts. Working Paper of the World Institute for Development Economics Research, WIDER, United Nations University, Helsinki. SHUE HENRY (1980) Basic. Rights; Subsistence. Affluence and U.S. Foreign Policy. Princeton University Press, Princeton, New Jersey. (1981) 'Exporting Hazards', in Peter Brown and Henry Shue (eds.) (198'), 'The Interdependence of Duties', in P. Alston and K. Tomasevski, (eds.) SINGER, PETER (1972) 'Famine, Affluence and Morality', Philosophy and. Public Affairs STIEHM. JUDITH HICKS (1983) "The Unit of Political Analysis: Our Aristotelian Hangover" in Sandra Harding and Merrill B. Hintikka eds. , Discovering Reality; Feminist Perspectives on Epistemology. Metaphysics. Methodology and Philosophy of Science. Reidel. Dordrecht, 31-43. WAL2ER, MICHAEL (1983) Spheres of. Justice: A Defence of Pluralism and Equality. Martin Robertson, Oxford. WILLIAMS, BERNARD (1985) Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy. Fontana. London. 39 WIDER WORKING PAPERS P 1. Amartya Sen: Food, economics and entitlements, February 1986 P 2. Nanak Kakwani: Decomposition of normalization axiom in the measurement of poverty: a comment, March 1986 P 3. Pertti Haaparanta: The intertemporal effects of international transfers, April 1986 P 4. Nanak Kakwani: Income inequality, welfare and poverty in a developing economy with applications to Sri Lanka, April 1986 P S. Pertti Haaparanta: and Juha Kahkonen: Liberalization of Capital Movements and Trade: Real Appreciation, Employment and Welfare, August 1986 Pertti Haaparanta: Dual Exchange Markets and Intervention, August 1986 Pertti Haaparanta: Real and Relative Wage Rigidities - Wage Indexation* in the Open Economy Staggered Contracts Model, August 1986 Nanak Kakwani: On Measuring Undernutrition, December 1986 Nanak Kakwani: Is Sex Bias Significant? December 1986 Partha Dasgupta and Debraj Ray: Adapting to Undernourishment: The Clinical Evidence and Its Implications, April 1987 Bernard Wood: Middle Powers in the International System: A Preliminary Assessment of Potential, June 1987 Stephany Griffith-Jones: The International Debt Problem - Prospects and Solutions, June 1987 Don Patinkin: Walras' Law, June 1987 Kaushik Basu: Technological Stagnation, Tenurial Laws and Adverse Selection, June 1987 Peter Svedberg: Undernutrition in Sub-Saharan Africa: A Critical Assessment of the Evidence, June 1987 S. R. Osmani: Controversies in Nutrition and their Implications for the Economics of Food, July 1987 Frederique Apffel Marglin: Smallpox in Two Systems of Knowledge, Revised, July 1987 Amartya Sen: Gender and Cooperative Conflicts, July 1987 Amartya Sen: Africa and India: What do we have to leam from each other? August 1987 Kaushik Basu: A Theory of Association: Social Status, Prices and Markets, August 1987 Kaushik Basu: A Theory of Surplus Labour, August 1987 Albert Fishlow: Some Reflections on Comparative Latin American Economic Performance and Policy, August 1987 Sukhamoy Chakravarty: Post-Keynesian Theorists and the Theory of Economic Development, August 1987 Georgy Skorov: Economic Reform in the USSR, August 1987 Amartya Sen: Freedom of Choice: Concept and Content, August 1987 Gopalakrishna Kumar: Ethiopian Famines 1973-1985: A Case-Study, November 1987 Carl Riskin: Feeding China: The Experience since 1949, November 1987 Martin Ravallion: Market Responses to Anti-Hunger Policies: Effects on Wages, Prices and Employment, November 1987 S. R. Osmani: The Food Problems of Bangladesh, November 1987 Martha Nussbaum and Amartya Sen: Internal Criticism and Indian Rationalist Traditions, December 1987 Martha Nussbaum: Nature, Function and Capability: Aristotle on Political Distribution, December 1987 Martha Nussbaum: Non-Relative Virtues: An Aristotelian Approach, December 1987 Tariq Banuri: Modernization and its Discontents A Perspective from the Sociology of Knowledge, December 1987 Alfred Maizels: Commodity Instability and Developing Countries: The Debate, January 1988 Jukka Pekkarinen. Keynesianism and the Scandinavian Models of Economic Policy, February 1988 Masahiko Aoki: A New Paradigm of Work Organization: The Japanese Experience, February 1988 Dragoslav Avramovic: Conditionality: Facts, Theory and Policy - Contribution to the Reconstruction of the International Financial System, February 1988 Gerald Epstein and Juliet Schor: Macropolicy in the Rise and Fall of the Golden Age, February 1988 Stephen Marglin and Amit Bhaduri: Profit Squeeze and Keynesian Theory, April 1988 Bob Rowthom and Andrew Glyn: The Diversity of Unemployment Experience Since 1973, April 1988 Lance Taylor: Economic Openness - Problems to the Century's End, April 1988 Alan Hughes and Ajit Singh: The World Economic Slowdown and the Asian and Latin American Economies: A Comparative Analysis of Economic Structure, Policy and Performance, April 1988 Andrew Glyn, Alan Hughes, Alan Lipietz and Ajit Singh: The Rise and Fall of of the Golden Age, April 1988 Jean-Philippe Platteau: The Food Crisis in Africa: A Comparative Structural Analysis, April 1988 Jean Dreze: Famine Prevention in India, May 1988 Peter Svedberg: A Model of Nutrition, Health and Economic Productivity, September 1988 Peter Svedberg: Undernutrition in Sub-Saharan Africa: Is There a Sex-Bias?, September 1988 S.R. Osmani: Wage Determination in Rural Labour Markets: The Theory of Implicit Co-operation, December 1988 S.R. Osmani: Social Security in South Asia, December 1988 S.R. Osmani: Food and the History of India - An 'Entitlement' Approach, December 1988 P 6. P 7. P 8. P 9. P 10. P 11. P 12. P 13. P 14. P 15. P 16. P 17. P 18. P 19. P 2 0 . P 2 1 . P 2 2 . P 2 3 . P 2 4 . P 2 5 . P 2 6 . P 2 7 . P 2 8 . P 2 9 . P 3 0 . P 3 1 . P 3 2 . P 3 3 . P 3 4 . P 3 5 . P 3 6 . P 3 7 . P 3 8 . P 3 9 . P 4 0 . P 4 1 . P 4 2 . P 4 3 . P 4 4 . P 4 5 . P 4 6 . P 4 7 . P 4 8 . P 4 9 . P 5 0 . WP 51. Grzegorz W. Kolodko: Reform, Stabilization Policies, and Economic Adjustment in Poland, January 1989 WP 52. Dariusz Rosati and Kalman Mizsei: Adjustment through Opening of Socialist Economies, January 1989 WP 53. Andrei Vemikov: Reforming Process and Consolidation in the Soviet Economy, January 1989 WP 54. Adam Torok: Stabilisation and Reform in the Hungarian Economy of the late 1980s, March 1989 WP 55. Zhang Yuyan: Economic System Reform in China, March 1989 WP 56. Amitava Krishna Dutt: Sectoral Balance: A Survey, March 1989 WP 57. Robert Pringle: Financial Markets and Governments, June 1989 WP 58. Marja-Liisa Swantz: Grassroots Strategies and Directed Development in Tanzania: The Case of the Fishing Sector, August 1989 WP 59. Aili Mari Tripp: Defending the Right to Subsist: The State vs. the Urban Informal Economy in Tanzania. August 1989 WP 60. Jacques H. Dreze, Albert Kervyn de Lettenhove, Jean-Philippe Platteau, Paul Reding: A Proposal for "Cooperative Relief of Debt in Africa" (CORDA), August 1989 WP 61. Kaushik Basu: Limited Liability and the Existence of Share Tenancy, August 1989 WP 62. Tariq Banuri: Black Markets, Openness, and Central Bank Autonomy, August 1989 WP 63. Amit Bhaduri: The Soft Option of the Reserve Currency Status, August 1989 WP 64. Andrew Glyn: Exchange Controls and Policy Autonomy - The Case of Australia 1983-88, August 1989 WP 65. Jaime Ros: Capital Mobility and Policy Effectiveness in a Solvency Crisis. The Mexican Economy in the 1980s, August 1989 WP 66. Dan W. Brock: Quality of Life Measures in Health Care and Medical Ethics, August 1989 WP 67. Robert Erikson: Descriptions of Inequality. The Swedish Approach to Welfare Research, August 1989 WP 68. Onora O'Neill: Justice, Gender and Internationa] Boundaries, August 1989 work_43zhqawqvjgwtfiyeyb7mbbk2u ---- King’s Research Portal DOI: 10.1093/ijtj/ijw022 Document Version Peer reviewed version Link to publication record in King's Research Portal Citation for published version (APA): Kerr, R. C. (2017). Tyrannies of Peace and Justice? Liberal Peacebuilding and the Politics and Pragmatics of Transitional Justice. International Journal Of Transitional Justice, 10(3), 176-185. https://doi.org/10.1093/ijtj/ijw022 Citing this paper Please note that where the full-text provided on King's Research Portal is the Author Accepted Manuscript or Post-Print version this may differ from the final Published version. If citing, it is advised that you check and use the publisher's definitive version for pagination, volume/issue, and date of publication details. And where the final published version is provided on the Research Portal, if citing you are again advised to check the publisher's website for any subsequent corrections. General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the Research Portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognize and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. •Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the Research Portal for the purpose of private study or research. •You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain •You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the Research Portal Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact librarypure@kcl.ac.uk providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 06. Apr. 2021 https://doi.org/10.1093/ijtj/ijw022 https://kclpure.kcl.ac.uk/portal/en/publications/tyrannies-of-peace-and-justice-liberal-peacebuilding-and-the-politics-and-pragmatics-of-transitional-justice(ab0f1e18-02ce-458e-ac66-4b3d9e3b5e7c).html https://doi.org/10.1093/ijtj/ijw022 1 Review essay: Tyrannies of Peace and Justice? Liberal Peacebuilding and the Politics and Pragmatics of Transitional Justice Rachel Kerr, King’s College London Mandy Turner and Florian P. Kühn (eds), The Politics of International Intervention: The Tyranny of Peace. Routledge Studies in Intervention and Statebuilding. (Abingdon: Routledge, 2016). ISBN: 978-1-138-89127-2 (hbk). 288pp. Annie R. Bird, US Foreign Policy on Transitional Justice (New York: Oxford University Press, 2015). ISBN: 978-0-199-33841-2 (hbk). 223pp. Laura Davis, EU Foreign Policy, Transitional Justice and Mediation: Principle, Policy and Practice. Routledge Studies in European Security and Strategy. (Abingdon: Routledge, 2014). ISBN: 978-0-415-74916-9 (hbk). 219pp. Transitional Justice has come to be regarded as a critical element of peacebuilding - a vital ‘tool’ in the United Nations’ peacebuilding kit. Over a decade ago, the then Secretary-General, Kofi Annan, formally recognised peace, justice and democracy as ‘mutually reinforcing imperatives’, 1 and argued that some form of transitional justice mechanism was crucial for societies emerging from violent conflict. The question was not whether to pursue TJ, but rather how. His 2011 Report on ‘The rule of law and transitional justice in conflict and post-conflict societies’, sought to put this into practice, focusing on the integration of TJ with related development and peacebuilding activities, such as judicial and security sector reform and rule of law and human rights programming. TJ in this context was not simply conceived of as a tool for addressing the past but to build a better future. 2 In this context, some have argued that TJ should address structural violence rather than focus exclusively on its legal and political manifestations.3 In a 2008 special issue of this journal, Rama Mani asked whether transitional justice could really afford not to concern itself with addressing patterns of social and economic injustice that are the root causes of conflict.4 Similarly, Wendy Lambourne set out wider conception of the relationship between transitional justice and peacebuilding, and proposed a model of transformative 1 ‘The rule of law and transitional justice in conflict and post-conflict societies’, Report of the Secretary General, S/2004/616, 23 August 2004. 2 Pablo de Grieff, ‘Transitional Justice, Security and Development: Security and Justice Thematic Paper’, World Development Report Background Paper (2011). See also, ‘The rule of law and transitional justice in conflict and post-conflict societies’, Report of the Secretary General, S/2011/634, 12 October 2011. 3 Rosemary Nagy, ‘Transitional Justice as a Global Project: Critical Reflections’, Third World Quarterly 29/2 (2008): 275-289. 4 Rama Mani, ‘Editorial: Dilemmas of Expanding Transitional Justice, or Forging the Nexus between Transitional Justice and Development’, International Journal of Transitional Justice 2 (2008): 253-265. 2 justice involving a ‘syncretic approach’ to restorative and retributive justice, recasting TJ it as part of a long-term process of transformation in the political, psychosocial and economic realms.5 The integration of TJ into the peacebuilding agenda is not without its critics, however. On the one hand, it has led to the expansion and recasting of the goals ascribed to TJ mechanisms which, coupled with the extremely challenging contexts in which it has been implemented, in societies riven by decades of conflict and with urgent security and development needs, has led to a considerable ‘gap’ between expectations and reality. On the other, if Transitional Justice and peacebuilding are inextricably intertwined, so are its critiques. In 2010, Roland Paris observed that the liberal peacebuilding project was at somewhat of a crossroads, having gone from ‘exuberance’ in the heady optimism of the early- to mid-1990s to its ‘denigration’ by ‘hyper-critical’ scholars who argue that it is fundamentally destructive and illegitimate, and has done more harm than good.6 Transitional justice as a field of study and practice appears to be at a similar crossroads. Rather than dogmatism, however, the debate has given space to fresh and critical voices – including recently in the pages of this journal – and reflection on the normative and political underpinnings of transitional justice embedded in both the liberal conception of human rights and liberal peacebuilding.7 To what extent does TJ suffer from the same weaknesses as the liberal peacebuilding project with which it is associated? Is there a ‘tyranny of justice’ embedded in the ‘tyranny of peace’, as some would have it? Or, like critiques of liberal peacebuilding are those of transitional justice, while often warranted, also exaggerated? 8 The three books under review address this question from very different vantage points. The Politics of International Intervention, edited by Mandy Turner and Florian P. Kühn, mounts a trenchant critique of the liberal ‘tyranny of peace’ whilst the other two volumes, by Annie Bird and Laura Davis, examine the TJ policies of liberal states – Bird’s focus is on US policy, while Davis sets her target on the EU. What all three books have in common is that they illustrate, in different ways, is an essential dilemma for transitional justice interventions, which is that in spite of what most take to be laudable motives driven by normative and pragmatic concerns in pursuit of justice and peace, the fruits of those labours are not always (ever?) what was intended. Rather, both TJ and peacebuilding are processes of highly contingent and imperfect transition, in which, just as there can be no one-size-fits- all solution, our notions of what constitutes success and failure also need to be carefully calibrated and contextualised. Transitional justice and the ‘tyranny’ of the liberal peace The Politics of International Intervention, edited by Mandy Turner and Florian P. Kühn, critically explores predominantly Western practices of peacebuilding and the politics that drive them before turning the tables around and exploring how communities who are subject to the ‘tyranny of peace[building]’ respond to, and experience international intervention. What Turner and Kühn’s book seeks to understand is how something apparently so normatively desirable – peace – has turned out so badly. That this has 5 Lambourne, ‘Transitional Justice and Peacebuilding after Mass Violence’. 6 Paris, Roland, ‘Saving Liberal Peacebuilding’, Review of International Studies 30/2 (2010): 338. 7 See, for example, Mutua, Makau, ‘What is the future of Transitional Justice?’, International Journal of Transitional Justice 9/1 (2015): 1-9; and Robins, Simon, ‘Mapping a Future for Transitional Justice by Learning from Its Past’, International Journal of Transitional Justice 9/1 (2015): 181-190. 8 Paris, Roland, ‘Saving Liberal Peacebuilding’, Review of International Studies 30/2 (2010): 337-365. 3 flummoxed policy-makers is illustrated neatly in the opening page of the book, with a quote from Tony Blair, former UK Prime Minister and Middle East Quartet representative, reflecting on interventions in Afghanistan, Iraq and Libya and support for the ‘Arab Spring’: ‘At first we jumped in to offer our support to those on the street. We are now bemused and bewildered that it hasn’t turned out quite how we expected.’ (p. 1) Whilst Turner and Kühn vehemently reject Blair’s diagnosis, they share his assessment of the symptoms – the pursuit of peacebuilding has indeed turned out badly as the region continues to be wracked by instability, violence and extremism (p. 1). However, whereas Blair locates the reason for failure in the broader ‘Titanic struggle’ between modernity and radical Islam, Turner and Kühn plant the blame firmly at the feet of the interveners rather than the intervened. Failure is cast not as a result of local inability to grasp what is traditionally cast as a benevolent project of liberal peacebuilding, but rather is located in the practices which, in contrast to its principles, reveal liberal peacebuilding to be a ‘hegemonic, tyrannical project’, engendering violent resistance (p. 2). Cast in this way, the liberal peace, like the colonial ‘mission civilisatrice’ (p. 8) before, and the ‘war on terror’ after, is but one of a series of justifications for Western violence in pursuit of the maintenance of power and position in the international system (p. 6). The book is organised in two sections. The first, ‘Exploring Peace’ is more conceptual, focused on the origins and development of the idea of the ‘liberal peace’. The second, ‘Imposing Peace’ focuses on particular instances, or interventions. The book broadens the scope of ‘intervention’ to include a ‘full spectrum of tools and policies’, including military operations, blockades, sanctions, aid and economic policies, but, notably, it does not encompass international judicial intervention or transitional justice as an element of the peacebuilding ‘toolkit’, so it is for us to extrapolate. Certainly, Turner and Kühn’s critique finds resonance in critiques of TJ.9 For example, Simon Robins tied TJ firmly to ‘liberal hegemony’, arguing that the goals of TJ ‘align perfectly with the integration of transitional states into global markets’.10 Moreover, like liberal peacebuilding, transitional justice interventions have been characterised by top-down approaches focused on the state and based on a checklist of TJ ‘tools’.11 In contrast, Robins calls for a ‘post-liberal, nonideological approach to addressing legacies of past violence’ that engages with the ‘everyday realities’ of those most affected by it.12 The challenge, however, is to find the right balance between, at one extreme, co-opting local actors through participation and consultation to embrace the values and mechanisms of TJ as currently practiced, and at the other, allowing the politics of resistance to derail TJ in the name of cultural relativism. In this context, Turner and Kühn’s work is important given that it explicitly rejects accounts that, in seeking to reverse the traditional privileging of the ‘international’, instead romanticise the ‘local’ as being somehow more ‘authentic’ (p. 5). Bruce Charbonneu’s chapter, for example, problematizes the dichotomy of ‘local’ and 9 See, for example, Gready, Paul and Simon Robins, ‘From Transitional to Transformative Justice: A New Agenda for Practice’, International Journal of Transitional Justice 8/3 (2014): 1-23; Millar, G. M., An Ethnographic Approach to Peacebuilding: Understanding Local Experiences in Transitional States (Routledge, Abingdon, 2014); Hopgood, Stephen, The Endtimes of Human Rights (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2013). 10 Robins, Simon, ‘Mapping a Future for Transitional Justice by Learning from Its Past’, International Journal of Transitional Justice 9/1 (2015): 186. 11 Sharp, D, ‘Interrogating the peripheries: the preoccupations of fourth-generation transitional justice’, Harvard Human Rights Journal (2013) 26: 149-178. 12 Robins, Simon, ‘Mapping a Future for Transitional Justice by Learning from Its Past’, International Journal of Transitional Justice 9/1 (2015): 187. 4 ‘international’ and ‘intervener’ and ‘intervened’ (Chapter 9). Rather, liberal peacebuilding, and the practices of transitional justice embedded in it, ought to be seen in the context of broader historical and conceptual understandings of intervention, justice, peace and resistance, which constitute, and are constitutive of, the international and domestic politics of interventions. This historical understanding is developed in Chapter 1, by Florian Kühn. For Kühn, the liberal peace is essentially about the expansion and protection of capitalist social relations and institutions – a combination of liberal internationalism and neoliberalism that ‘renders alternative forms of peace unthinkable’ (Chapter 1). In Chapter 2, Scott Kirsh and Colin Flint dismantle the war/peace dichotomy at the heart of the concept of ‘post-conflict reconstruction’, positing it as a continuation of violence through the imposition of a particular form of state, economy, culture and society. In Chapters 3 and 4, Phillip Cunliffe and Michael Pugh critique the practice of the UN. Cunliffe takes issue with the UN’s claim to be implementing peacebuilding that consciously differs from practices of colonialism, demonstrating that colonialism remains the ‘spectre at the feast’ as UN practices restrict the range of options available, forcing conformity with liberal political organisation and a market capitalist society. Pugh’s chapter follows on by demonstrating that a UN-mandated peace is an ‘aggressive peace’, characterised by militarised violence and a political economy of peacebulding. Finally, in this Part, Heidi Hudson, demonstrates how the appropriation of women as passive ‘victims’ (of sexual and gender-based violence) in the discourse of liberal peacebuilding perpetuates women’s disempowerment. This theme is emerging as an alternative narrative in the transitional justice literature, seeking to dismantle dominant gendered narratives of transitional justice interventions and to disengage the notion of women solely as passive ‘good’ victims and focus instead on structural inequalities and their role as agents.13 Part 2 comprises a set of eight case studies of international intervention, all in the post- Cold war era of liberal peacebuilding. In Chapter 6, Caroline Hughes analyses Cambodia; in Chapter 7 Mandy Turner looks at Palestine; Chapter 8 by Astri Surkhe examines the politics of international intervention in Afghanistan; Chapter 9 by Bruce Charbonneau analyses the series of interventions leading to eventual regime change (and referral to the ICC) in Cote d’Ivoire; in Chapter 10, Toby Dodge dissects the intervention in Iraq in the context of ideational understandings of the nature of Saddam’s regime by policy makers in the West; Chapter 11 by Nicolas Pelham shows how the lessons learned from the process of de-Ba’athification were mis-applied in Libya, where the ‘old guard’ were integrated, alienating rebel groups in the process; Chapter 12 by Bruno Charbonnaeu and Jonathan Sears focuses on the French intervention in Mali, where the discourse of global Islamic terrorism overlay context-specific dynamics that ought to have been more fully addressed; and finally, in Chapter 13, Christopher Phillips analyses international intervention (and non-intervention) in Syria. These studies are detailed and instructive and, while they do not focus specifically on transitional justice policies and practices, they are nevertheless significant in contributing to understanding of the context in which transitional justice interventions are made, and in shedding light on an essential dilemma in transitional justice – in particular international criminal justice – which is that the outcomes are not always as one would hope or expect. An essentially 13 Campbell, Kirsten, ‘The Gender of Transitional Justice: Law, Sexual Violence and the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia’ International Journal of Transitional Justice (2007) 1 (3): 411-432; and Ramona Vijeyarasa, ‘Women at the Margins of International Law: Reconceptualizing Dominant Discourses on Gender and Transitional Justice’ International Journal of Transitional Justice (2013) 7 (2): 358-369. 5 normative project to deliver justice and, with it, peace, often delivers neither to the satisfaction of the communities experiencing judicial intervention, or indeed to those intervening who do not see measurable ‘impact’. As the contributions to Turner and Kühn’s book make clear, in order to understand this, we need to take a much closer look at the politics and practices of the communities in question, and dissect the ways in which international actors influence particular contexts and interact with local actors in ways that are not always directly visible (p. 3). In focusing on US and policy, respectively, Bird and Davis go some way toward this goal, showing how TJ policy is formulated by liberal states with – arguably – shared liberal norms and cultures but different political and pragmatic concerns. What they do not engage with however, is the ‘domestic politics’ of transitional justice – the politics of resistance and co-optation. Liberal tyranny in practice? US policy Annie Bird’s US Foreign Policy on Transitional Justice tells us what US policy on transitional justice looks like, how it is formulated and what informs it. As Bird makes clear, the US is a key player in the field of transitional justice – and in particular international criminal justice. It is one of the largest donors and contributes ‘in kind’ technical expertise and political support at critical junctures. Bird even goes so far as to say that without US sponsorship, many transitional justice measures would not have been established (p. 150). Bird attributes US policy to a mix of normative and pragmatic motives and concerns, casting it as ‘symbolic, retributive and strategic’ (p. 2). Symbolic, in that it resonates with the powerful role that the notion of ‘justice’ plays in American society; retributive, because retribution is generally preferred over other forms of transitional justice, which may have a more restorative function, such as truth commissions, which is also predicated in the American faith in the rule of law. And strategic because the normative drive for justice is tempered by a more pragmatic balancing of interests in the US foreign policy bureaucracy (p. 151). The book’s major contribution is to detail how this balancing of interests and values plays out. The book’s strength is its detailed account of the three case studies – Cambodia, Liberia and Columbia – and its account of the multiple sources that underpin US foreign policy (p. 153). What all three cases have in common is a legacy of US interest and involvement, and the fact that the US was key stakeholder, influencing transitional justice policy and practice. These chapters are rich in detail regarding the formulation of US policy and the machinations of the US political apparatus. A really intriguing aspect is the role of individuals – a story that is less often told but nevertheless quite significant is the story not of epistemic communities,14 but rather what we might term ‘epistemic individuals’ in the world of international criminal justice. Just as international judges have a uniquely privileged and powerful position from within international courts to influence the development of what has hitherto been a lightly adjudicated body of law, those involved at the legal-political interface, creating courts and drafting statutes have also had significant influence. As have, of course, the Chief Prosecutors of the various courts and tribunals, and Bird points out similarities between Jackson and Crane, for example (p. 91). Other familiar figures are also in evidence, and many of these gave interviews to Bird, offering considerable insight not only into the US policy-making process, but also into their own perceptions and role. This includes of course the 14 Schiff, Benjamin, Building the International Criminal Court (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008), 51. 6 testimonies of key players in US transitional justice policy as Ambassadors at Large for War Crimes Issues, David Scheffer, Pierre Prosper, Clint Williamson, and Stephen Rapp (interview list, p. 176). Whilst in each case, there is a legacy of US interest and involvement; the contexts are of course otherwise quite different. In Cambodia, the US, having opposed earlier efforts to seek accountability for the crimes committed by the Khmer Rouge, the US eventually lent their support to a UN-brokered deal with the Cambodian Government to establish a Tribunal. In Liberia, the picture was complicated by the establishment of the Special Court for Sierra Leone, which while it did not have jurisdiction for Liberia, did extend its jurisdiction to Liberia’s President Charles Taylor for crimes committed in Sierra Leone. The story of justice in Liberia that Bird tells is largely concerned with the story of how Taylor was eventually brought to trial by the Special Court, sitting in special session at the ICC in The Hague. Finally, in Colombia transitional justice policy was formulated in the context of a fragile negotiated end of years of civil war, at various times characterised by the Colombian and US governments as a counter-narcotics, counter-terrorism or counter-insurgency (p. 125-6). All three cases involved compromise and careful balancing of interests of justice and peace. Missing from her analysis, however, is a more historical and contextualised understanding of US engagement in Liberia, that might have been better informed by applying the critique offered in Turner and Kühn’s book, which would cast US transitional justice policy in Liberia, for example, as not simply a product of balancing of interests at play, but constituted by, and constitutive of, the quasi-colonial legacy of US involvement in Liberia, and conditioned the relationship between international – in this case the US – and local politics. In all three cases, one could argue that not only were US interests directly involved, beyond a normative interest in justice and peace for the countries concerned; US policy was also conditioned by the historical legacy of US involvement and the policies and prejudices inherent in that legacy, some of which created the conditions for human rights abuses to be tolerated in the first place. The book’s primary focus is the story of US involvement in transitional justice, and it tells this story well in respect of the three cases, but the narrative approach somewhat precludes a more critical approach to US foreign policy formulation on a subject in which it had varying degrees of interest and involvement, and in the end, was also subject to the whim of others, in particular those more directly involved and implicated in the different cases, such as the Governments of Cambodia, Liberia and Columbia. It also precludes discussion of the constituencies at which transitional justice is aimed, as Bird acknowledges in her conclusion, when she argues that the US approach needs to take better account of the preferences and needs of these (victims) populations (p. 156). The overarching focus on the US as the driver of transitional justice interventions means that there is a tendency for Bird to cast the results as products of shifts in US policy, rather than the complex mix of international and domestic dynamics, and the discussion tends to privilege the role of the US over other parties – states and international organisations. Early on, for example, in discussing the adoption of a more robust policy on arresting ICTY indictees, Bird makes no mention of the pivotal role played by the UK Government in deciding to carry out the first detention operation by international forces in Bosnia in July 1997. And, in discussion of the negotiations leading to the adoption of the Justice and Peace Law in Colombia, and its implementation, no mention is made of the role of the ICC Prosecutor, who exerted influence by exerting its positive 7 complementarity mandate – an aspect of the ICC that merits close attention as it is here that it has the opportunity to make a difference by encouraging national level prosecutions, and also here that it operates at the nexus of law and politics, having carefully to balance political and legal considerations to determine the ‘interests of justice’. Taking up Turner and Kühn’s critique, this book perpetuates an understanding of transitional justice as part of a project that can be implemented as part of the dissemination of liberal values, and in pursuit of a liberal peace, rather than an examination of how the values that inform US policy are mediated in implementation, not just by constraints and contradictions in the US political machinery, but also by politics on the ground. It is also uncritical of the values embedded in US policy, in particular the system of retributive justice which others have argued is at the centre of a degrading system of coercion and control that perpetuates racial divisions and inequality in the US.15 The book is disappointingly thin on the historical evolution of US foreign policy. It relies on Gary Bass’ earlier study of international justice policy, Stay the Hand of Vengeance, although it does take his argument about legalism driving US policy and develop it into one about symbolism and retribution. It would have been interesting and worthwhile to delve a little deeper into the mechanics of foreign policy formulation around Nuremberg and especially in the years between Nuremberg and the manifestation of its legacy, with the establishment of the ICTY, in 1993. This is a story that hasn’t properly been told, and would, I suspect, be informative. More attention might also have been given to the negotiations leading to the Rome Statute and establishment of the ICC, and in particular the signing and un-signing of the Rome Statute. The period leading up to, and during the negotiations at Rome is crucial to understanding the mix of legalism, politics and pragmatism that underpins US policy.16 Opposition to the court was not simply a case of wanting to protect US citizens from its jurisdiction but predicated on a different conception of what the court should be – an instrument of international peace and security that could be wielded when appropriate for the interests of peace, rather than a separate instrument of international justice, with the power to act when it saw fit.17 A more niggling point is that the book repeats inaccuracies (the figure of 200,000 killed is cited for Bosnia, whereas it was closer to 100,000, p. 37)18 and suffers from an uncritical repetition of familiar tropes attributed to ‘observers’ – that the ICTY was to relieve obligation to do more (p. 40), that support for the SCSL was part of opposition to the ICC (p. 42), and that the use of the word genocide by then Secretary of State Colin Powell in respect of Darfur was what led to the opening up on an inquiry (p. 42). All of these points could be interrogated more closely, revealing greater nuance than is acknowledged here. Bureaucratic politics and a pragmatic approach: the EU Laura Davis’, EU Foreign Policy, Transitional Justice and Mediation, provides us with a detailed and nuanced account of the formulation of transitional justice policy in the EU in the context of a solid understanding of the complex and bureaucratic processes of foreign 15 George Nickolas Fourlas, ‘No Future without Transition: A Critique of the Liberal Peace’, IJTJ (2015) 9/1: 109-126. 16 Kaufman, Zachary, United States Law and Policy on Transitional Justice: Principles, Politics, and Pragmatics (Oxford University Press 2016). 17 See, Kerr, Rachel and Eirin Mobekk. Peace and Justice: Seeking Accountability After War (Cambridge: Polity, 2007). 18 According to the Bosnian Book of the Dead, complied by the Sarajevo Research and Documentation Centre, see: http://www.balkaninsight.com/en/article/justice-report-bosnia-s-book-of-the-dead. http://www.balkaninsight.com/en/article/justice-report-bosnia-s-book-of-the-dead 8 policy formulation more broadly. Viewed through a normative vs. pragmatism lens, EU foreign policy comes across as resolutely pragmatic. Like US policy, it is underpinned by liberal principles at the core of the EU project – respect for human rights and the rule of law – but implemented in a more ad hoc and contextualised manner in response to changes on the ground rather than any broader strategic shifts. Davis discusses EU foreign policy in the context of the transitional justice literature and shows how the EU is as muddled as the rest of us when it comes to determining what it is and how it should best be applied. As she demonstrates, TJ is not embedded in a common foreign and security policy, but rather exists at the margins – so it is not an integral part of intervention but is nevertheless an important element. There is no overarching policy, but rather a piecemeal approach to transitional justice, which, Davis argues, poses significant challenges to effective engagement (p. 73). Davis does not spend much time on the EU’s complementarity strategy for the Western Balkans, which is surprising, given that it was so significant in the story of transitional justice in that region. It was an innovative approach, born of both normative and pragmatic motives – to ensure accountability and, it was hoped, contribute to reconciliation, and also to foster political change and speed the transition to stable democracy. The outcome was mixed: it enabled the ICTY to function and forced some change, but there was also blowback, the results of which are now evident in the resurgence of nationalist parties, although that cannot entirely be laid at conditionality’s door. The major contribution this book makes, however, is its careful and detailed case study of EU involvement in transitional justice interventions, policy and practice in the DRC. The DRC makes an excellent case study because as Davis makes clear, the EU was so intimately involved, and all of its crisis management and conflict prevention instruments were deployed (p. 127). The DRC also provided a testing ground for a range of transitional justice mechanisms – referral to the ICC, domestic prosecutions, a limited amnesty regime, and a truth and reconciliation commission, and, as Valerie Arnould explains elsewhere, it was domestic rather than international actors who largely defined the transitional justice agenda in the DRC, motivated by overlapping political and moral concerns about legitimacy, the desire to frame a particular historical narrative, the appeasement of inter-communal tensions, the denunciation of foreign aggression and pragmatic imperatives dictated by on-going violence in the east. 19 Davis expands the discussion of transitional justice mechanisms also to encompass reform of the security and justice systems, which adds another important dimension to our understanding, especially in the context of the role and function of TJ in relation to peacebuilding or post-conflict reconstruction. The chapter on the DRC provides a detailed account of all of the various interventions made by the EU, but the bigger picture supports the observation made earlier, that the lack of an overarching policy and the implementation of a piecemeal approach was exposed in the DRC. Gaps between principle and practice widened in respect of security sector reform, where the provision of technical assistance took precedence over engaging the Congolese authorities on human rights issues (p. 158). In other areas, there was a ‘policy vacuum’ (for example, on the question of amnesties in peace negotiations, p. 158), but not an absence of 19 Arnould, Valerie, The Politics of Transitional Justice and Peacebuilding: The Case of the Democratic Republic of the Congo (London: Routledge, 2015). 9 principle, so that in the absence of clear policy guidelines, the EU Special Representative followed a principled approach consistent with support for accountability (p. 181). Her conclusion is insightful. Whilst overall, Davis argues that EU policy is unevenly applied and implemented; on the other hand, it is consistently inconsistent (my emphasis) across the different pillars (p. 162). Arguably, this allows for greater flexibility, but equally Davis argues that stronger coherence and better coordination not only internally between EU instruments, but also between the EU and other international actors might have enabled domestic actors who prioritised transitional justice to be more effective (p. 166), and more broadly would enhance the EU’s credibility as an advocate of justice and peace (p. 204). Recalling the critiques of TJ, however it shows that TJ, as an element of a wider peacebuilding effort, was not applied uncritically, regardless of context, but it might nevertheless have been somewhat hampered by the constraints discussed above, of operating with a conception of TJ as a ‘toolkit’ to be applied as and when different options become feasible. Davis’ study of EU policy also begs the question of what the future role of the EU is vis- à-vis other actors in the transitional justice arena? Does it have the normative power and influence of a few years ago, post economic crisis? Is it too mired in its own problems, with migration and possible Brexit? Equally, for the US, an issue not discussed by Bird is the extent to which the US has squandered its normative capital by flouting the law. Guantanamo, and especially the revelations of abuse at Abu Ghraib undermined the US stance on the ICC and its position as a soft power exporter of liberty, the rule of law and human rights. And, echoing Bird, if we privilege strategic or pragmatic goals over the more normative or principled ones, are we really doing ‘justice’ to those for whom transitional justice is ostensibly for, or are we, circling back to Turner and Kühn, simply reinforcing the tyrannies of a liberal peace? Whither TJ? Transitional justice is, in number of important respects, at a critical juncture. Critiques of TJ highlight the ways in which it is inextricably tied to the liberal peacebuilding project, which is predicated on preserving a ‘liberal hegemony’, and the ways in which it is challenged by resistance to the norms and values underpinning it. This manifests most visibly in resistance to the International Criminal Court. However, whilst both TJ and liberal peacebuilding have their weaknesses, casting the TJ ‘industry’ as a ‘decontextualised mantra’ seems a little overblown.20 As Davis’ study of the EU demonstrates, context matters to at least some of the policy makers implementing TJ. The challenge, as ever, is to navigate heavily contingent processes of transition, and carefully balance norms, values, politics and pragmatics, as well as to take account of the range of actors and interests involved. If we want to ‘save’ TJ (in similar vein to Roland Paris’ quest to ‘save’ liberal peacebuilding),21 we need to be realistic about what it can achieve and honest about what it cannot. And we need to move away from the assumption of an institutional and state-based approach to one that recognises and accommodates the interaction of a range of international and domestic actors, cultures (norms), politics (resistance), and pragmatics. 20 Robins, Simon, ‘Mapping a Future for Transitional Justice by Learning from Its Past’, International Journal of Transitional Justice 9/1 (2015): 190. 21 Paris, Roland, ‘Saving Liberal Peacebuilding’, Review of International Studies 30/2 (2010): 337-365. work_463slpxfsrdmtn6hs7h6amvhau ---- to provide a powerful new analytical framework for the study of international relations, which nevertheless also retains the unique qualities and advantages of the classical English School tradition. By making the English School more theoretically self-conscious and situating its contributions within more recent developments in the International Relations literature, Buzan has turned a tradition, whose fortunes had arguably been languishing, into a vibrant research programme, which will have considerable appeal to a younger generation of IR theorists. References Buzan, B. (1993) ‘From international system to international society: structural realism and regime theory meet the english school’, International Organisation 47(3): 327–352. Ewan Harrison The Queen’s College, Oxford, UK. Justice in the Risk Society Barbara Hudson Sage Publications, London, 2003, xviiþ258pp. ISBN: 0 7619 6160 7. Contemporary Political Theory (2005) 4, 353–355. doi:10.1057/palgrave.cpt.9300209 Imagine Seyla Benhabib standing in for Jerry Springer, or Jurgen Habermas standing in for Oprah Winfrey, or Judith Butler standing in for Judge Judy. Imagine Michael Walzer presenting Neighbours from Hell or Carole Pateman presenting Wife Swap or Iris Marion Young presenting Crimewatch UK. These possibilities might spring to mind when reading Barbara Hudson’s Justice in the Risk Society because they capture the central problem the book establishes and explores. In the 1980s and 90s, sociologists such as Ulrich Beck observed that for a range of reasons the contingency of modernity had become reflexive. Because nothing could be guaranteed, life became a matter of more risk and less trust. Thus, if, for one reason or another, individuals reject the guarantees which the state and its institutions provide for them, they will have to bear the consequences themselves. Unfortunately, such an imperative has been very difficult for most people to swallow categorically. Instead, unregulated social life is generally viewed as a matter of getting caught or getting away with it. Above all, the trick is to find someone else to blame, and thus the moral advantage of someone else to fear. Book Reviews 353 Contemporary Political Theory 2005 4 In the face of these attitudes the dominant modern liberal approach to legal practice and jurisprudence is powerless to establish its own legitimacy in its own terms because these are not shared, accepted or recognised by legal subjects except for instrumental or, as Rawls said, ‘wrong’ reasons. Moreover, the self-serving liberal assumption that individuals are rational insofar as they agree with its axioms and accept its conclusions is simply ignored without the bother of argument or debate. Devastatingly, whereas liberalism justified the appropriation of a monopoly of force on the basis that doing so guarantees individual protection, individuals now regard states and their systems as a resource to be used as a means to further their own individual ends and demand to receive at least the equivalent of what they contribute to it. No one is prepared to pay the cost of entering into a covenant of obedience in return for creating jobs for civil servants. Similarly, the democratic conscience of liberalism, which sought to set limits to state action in order to protect individuals from it, has the status of a weakness to be exploited. Individuals regard their conflicts with the state as of the same order as their conflicts with other individuals, and their conflicts with the state often derive from its refusal to support them in pursuit of their aims. When distributive justice has become the distribution of justice how is justice possible? Barbara Hudson’s book addresses the issue in two parts. The first four chapters discuss the main challenges to the liberal tradition, with the second, on the complex contemporary relations between legal practice, policing and criminology and welfare, being particularly enlightening. For example, in order to manage and control risk, it has been suggested that individuals deemed to demonstrate the potential to develop serious personality disorders are eligible for legal constraint. The dominant trend on the front line is to develop therapeutic approaches that seek reconciliation by working on individual subjectivities. In either case everyone is ‘at risk’. But what is interesting about these developments is that they demonstrate how the state and its legal and penal systems are primarily concerned to protect themselves from risk and to demonstrate that they have ‘systems in place’ to do that and to reduce their own exposure to liability. The emphasis of Hudson’s book is on finding philosophical justifications for such practices. In addition to a first chapter outlining the internal tensions of liberalism, the other chapters in the section provide accounts of the philosophical and sociological communitarian critiques of liberal procedures and the feminist critique of liberal universalism. These themes are taken up in the three chapters of the second section which seek to find arguments that will reaffirm liberal justice in the light of its critiques. Hudson examines Habermas’s attempt to reconcile the ‘fact and norm’ of rational agreement through communicative consensus with his sympathetic feminist critics and suggests that this approach can contribute to weakening popular desires for retribution. To further the Book Reviews 354 Contemporary Political Theory 2005 4 issue, Hudson turns to developments associated with poststructuralist thought and in particular Lyotard’s emphasis on the incommensurability of justice as its internal limit, and Levinas’s ethic of unconditional responsibility to the ‘ultra-other’. Each chapter of Hudson’s book stands alone for its scholarship, exposition and readability and can be applauded and recommended for that reason. Yet it is difficult to get a sense of an overall argument adequate to the empirical challenges of risk society rather than the immanent philosophical critiques of liberalism. Some people will still fire bomb each others houses because of some obscure vendetta, and other people will still pay to exclude themselves from that society, and both types will avoid contributing to their own subjection, irrespective of what Habermas says about it. For example, one wonders how Levinas’s notion of the Other, by which he meant Abraham’s God and not Palestinians, could establish justice in the test case of the stereotypical conflict between the freedom seeking Muslim daughter and the tradition upholding Muslim parents, which Hudson discusses. Levinas would probably decide in favour of tradition, yet the case is only a case for liberalism. Indeed, one suspects that the poststructuralist emphasis on the ‘alterity’ and ‘incommen- surability’ of justice might be used self-servingly by legal professionals and their support agencies as justification for law as an interminable process in which individuals may or may not get caught up. Perhaps the challenge of risk society requires further sociological research into how the legal system or, more accurately, ‘network’, plays its own risk creation and avoidance games in order to protect and expand its interests? Doing so could contribute to a philosophical critique of the content of law, beginning with the expensive stupidity of the persistence of premodern sumptuary laws such as those which criminalise the enjoyment of narcotics in which the interests of law and crime coincide exactly. Jeremy Valentine Queen Margaret University College, Edinburgh, UK. Book Reviews 355 Contemporary Political Theory 2005 4 Justice in the Risk Society work_4bjrzfxnpjbwjdm5vx35wuarka ---- [PDF] XENOTRANSPLANTATION, CONSENT AND INTERNATIONAL JUSTICEdewb_251 119..127 | Semantic Scholar Skip to search formSkip to main content> Semantic Scholar's Logo Search Sign InCreate Free Account You are currently offline. Some features of the site may not work correctly. Corpus ID: 49579789XENOTRANSPLANTATION, CONSENT AND INTERNATIONAL JUSTICEdewb_251 119..127 @inproceedings{Sparrow2009XENOTRANSPLANTATIONCA, title={XENOTRANSPLANTATION, CONSENT AND INTERNATIONAL JUSTICEdewb_251 119..127}, author={R. Sparrow}, year={2009} } R. Sparrow Published 2009 researchmgt.monash.edu Save to Library Create Alert Cite Launch Research Feed Share This Paper References in Primates : World Experience and Current Status Xenotransplantation 1998 Related Papers Abstract 1 References Related Papers Stay Connected With Semantic Scholar Sign Up About Semantic Scholar Semantic Scholar is a free, AI-powered research tool for scientific literature, based at the Allen Institute for AI. Learn More → Resources DatasetsSupp.aiAPIOpen Corpus Organization About UsResearchPublishing PartnersData Partners   FAQContact Proudly built by AI2 with the help of our Collaborators Terms of Service•Privacy Policy The Allen Institute for AI By clicking accept or continuing to use the site, you agree to the terms outlined in our Privacy Policy, Terms of Service, and Dataset License ACCEPT & CONTINUE work_4elsvwcdhfge7dbskh3iwfjjjy ---- The European Journal of International Law Vol. 21 no. 4 © EJIL 2011; all rights reserved .......................................................................................... EJIL (2010), Vol. 21 No. 4, 1085–1102 doi: 10.1093/ejil/chq070 Imperfect Justice at Nuremberg and Tokyo Kirsten Sellars* Guénaël Mettraux (ed). Perspectives on the Nuremberg Trial. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008. Pp. 832. £36.99. ISBN 978019923234. Neil Boister and Robert Cryer. The Tokyo International Military Tribunal: A Reappraisal. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008. Pp. 358. £63.50. ISBN 9780199278527. Yuma Totani. The Tokyo War Crimes Trial: The Pursuit of Justice in the Wake of World War II. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 2009. Pp. 355. $22.95. ISBN 9780674033399. Abstract When the international criminal tribunals were convened in Nuremberg and Tokyo in the mid-1940s, the response from lawyers was mixed. Some believed that the Second World War was an exceptional event requiring special legal remedies, and commended the tribunals for advancing international law. Others condemned them for their legal shortcomings and maintained that some of the charges were retroactive and selectively applied. Since then, suc- cessive generations of commentators have interpreted the tribunals in their own ways, shaped by the conflicts and political concerns of their own times. The past two decades have seen the establishment of new international courts, and an accompanying revival of interest in their predecessors at Nuremberg and Tokyo. Recent commentaries have analysed the founding documents, the choice of defendants, the handling of the charges, the conduct of the cases – and also the legal and political legacies of the tribunals. They demonstrate that long-standing disagreements over antecedents, aims and outcomes have still not been settled, and that the problems inherent in some of the original charges have still not been solved, despite the appearance of similar charges within the remit of the International Criminal Court today. * PhD, Aberdeen University’s School of Law. Her first book, The Rise and Rise of Human Rights, was published in 2002; her next book, The ‘Supreme’ Crime: Crimes Against Peace and International Law, is forthcoming. a t N e w Y o rk U n ive rsity o n F e b ru a ry 1 , 2 0 1 1 e jil.o xfo rd jo u rn a ls.o rg D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://ejil.oxfordjournals.org/ 1086 EJIL 21 (2010), 1085–1102 No document better conveys the roughness and expediency of the negotiations lead- ing up to the postwar tribunal at Nuremberg than the transcript of the four-power London Conference held from late June to early August 1945.1 At this gathering, which was book-ended by the signing of the UN Charter and the bombing of Hiro- shima, the Allies formally discussed the proposal to set up a court to try the captured German leaders. In the event, the conference very nearly broke down. The American delegate threatened to walk out over the question of the court’s location, the French delegate objected to plans to bring charges of crimes against peace, the British fretted over the risk of German countercharges, and the Soviets refused to countenance a def- inition of aggression. The debates were in turn acrimonious, meandering, portentous, repetitive and disjointed. There were frequent misunderstandings between common and civil law delegates, and all were compelled to advance their respective nation’s interests. Until the final day, none of them could be sure that a tribunal would be established at all, let alone that their discussions would provide the conceptual frame- work for two great assizes, one in Nuremberg, the other in Tokyo. This was history in the making, and its making was a messy and unedifying business. In the 65 years since the London Conference and the international tribunals that followed in its wake, successive generations of commentators, writing with the benefit of hindsight, have offered their appraisals of this postwar experiment in international criminal justice. It is notable that these interpretations were often shaped in response to the wars of their own time. In the early 1950s, for example, Western conservatives argued that a new war with the Soviets was in the offing, and the time for prosecuting the Germans had passed. In the late 1960s, Bertrand Russell and Jean-Paul Sartre staged their own informal ‘tribunal’ to condemn American crimes in Vietnam. In the early 1990s, both Margaret Thatcher (in reference to Iraq) and Madeleine Albright (to Bosnia) harked back to the Nuremberg ideal. Until recently, however, it was widely assumed that the large-scale formally consti- tuted international tribunals of the 1940s were an experiment that was not likely to be repeated: as Geoffrey Best wrote in the closing decade of the Cold War, Nuremberg was ‘but a beacon behind us, growing ever fainter’.2 But with the revival of interest in inter- national criminal law after the fall of the Berlin Wall, the postwar tribunals assumed a new significance to the lawyers and policy-makers involved in the newly constituted ad hoc courts and International Criminal Court, who found themselves grappling with many of the same problems. What was the most appropriate method for determining individual responsibility for international crimes? What were the problems associated with the criminalization of aggression or the prosecution of crimes against humanity? How might one organize a case if documentary evidence or witnesses were not readily available? These questions and many others are considered in the three books under 1 United States Department of State, Report of Robert H Jackson, United States Representative to the Inter- national Conference on Military Trials, London, 1945. 2 G. Best, Nuremberg and After: The Continuing History of War Crimes and Crimes Against Humanity (1984), at 26. a t N e w Y o rk U n ive rsity o n F e b ru a ry 1 , 2 0 1 1 e jil.o xfo rd jo u rn a ls.o rg D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://ejil.oxfordjournals.org/ Imperfect Justice at Nuremberg and Tokyo 1087 review, which provide fascinating insights into the conceptualization of the charges, the conduct of the trials, the findings that they made, and, finally, the respective leg- acies of Nuremberg and Tokyo. Each book has different approaches and different strengths, and together they provide a very substantial appraisal of the two tribunals. 1 The Conception of Nuremberg The Nuremberg Tribunal, shorn of its least palatable features, has now become the lodestar of international criminal justice. The lawyer Guénaël Mettraux’s major 32-article anthology of writings on this tribunal covers law, history, politics and phil- osophy, and includes important pieces newly translated from the French, German and Russian. It begins, appropriately enough, with contributions by two men who played a pivotal role in the trial’s conception: American chief prosecutor Robert Jackson and his intellectual collaborator Hersch Lauterpacht. In late 1940, Jackson (then attorney- general) began to consult Lauterpacht on the problem of how to justify the United States’ involvement in the war at a time when the nation was still avowedly neutral. His Havana speech of March 1941 incorporated Lauterpacht’s suggestions relating to ‘qualified neutrality’,3 the punishment of aggression, and just war theory. And his Indianapolis speech of October, reprinted in the anthology, issued an internationalist challenge to residual isolationism by calling for a strengthening of international law to deal with aggression and maintain peace.4 Hersch Lauterpacht once again dispensed advice to Jackson when they met in July 1945 to discuss the charges that were being formulated at the London Conference, and he later helped to write British chief prosecutor Hartley Shawcross’s opening and closing speeches at the trial itself. His ideas were compelling, and some of them – such as those on the individual and the state – were later voiced by Shawcross in court, then reproduced in the Judgment. Jackson and Lauterpacht were central figures who obviously should be included in the anthology, but other highly influential individu- als who contributed to the construction of the charges have been left out. Notable omissions include the Soviet academic Aron N Trainin, and the American lawyers Murray Bernays and William Chanler, who in the latter half of 1944 began to inde- pendently formulate the charges that would later appear in the Nuremberg Charter as ‘common plan or conspiracy’ and ‘crimes against peace’.5 3 Jackson, ‘Address of Robert H. Jackson, Attorney General of the United States, Inter-American Bar Asso- ciation, Havana, Cuba, March 27, 1941’, 35 AJIL (1941) 348, at 351. 4 Jackson, ‘The Challenge of International Lawlessness’ (1941), in Mettraux, at 11. 5 A. N. Trainin, A. Y. Vishinski (ed) and A. Rothstein (tr), Hitlerite Responsibility Under Criminal Law (1945); Bernays, ‘Legal Basis of the Nuremberg Trials’, 35 Survey Graphic (1946) 4; and Bernays documents in B. F. Smith, The American Road to Nuremberg: The Documentary Record 1944–1945 (1982); Chanler docu- ments in Bush, ‘“The Supreme . . . Crime” and its Origins: The Lost Legislative History of the Crime of Aggressive War’, 102 Colum L Rev (2002) 2324. a t N e w Y o rk U n ive rsity o n F e b ru a ry 1 , 2 0 1 1 e jil.o xfo rd jo u rn a ls.o rg D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://ejil.oxfordjournals.org/ 1088 EJIL 21 (2010), 1085–1102 Despite careful planning by the prosecuting powers, underlying tensions meant that they were unable to follow a consistent line at Nuremberg. They were prepared to countenance the revolutionary idea of holding national leaders to account (so long as it was at an ad hoc trial), but they were also aware of the sovereignty-piercing implications of the charges, and thus treated them with circumspection. Responding to these tensions, Robert Jackson adopted different positions at different times: some- times he was an impeccable naturalist, other times an unabashed realist. Yet despite the innovative features of the trial he had helped to convene, his preoccupation with sovereign rights never wavered, which is why, in his closing speech, he was moved to state that ‘[t]he intellectual bankruptcy and moral perversion of the Nazi regime might have been no concern to international law had it not been utilized to goosestep the Herrenvolk across international frontiers’.6 2 Critics and Criticisms In the first half of Mettraux’s anthology, which deals with contemporaneous perspec- tives on the trial, a range of participants discuss the conception of the charges, the presentation of the evidence, and the significance of the judgment. These writings by, among others, Jackson’s legal colleagues and political allies – Francis Biddle, Thomas Dodd, Telford Taylor, Herbert Wechsler, Quincy Wright, and in a later section, Henry Stimson – provide rich pickings, but they also highlight the book’s one serious flaw. When covering the immediate postwar period, it thoroughly documents the more commendatory approaches to the Tribunal, yet it does not do the same for the argu- ments against, even though the criticisms were powerful enough to compel the pros- ecuting powers in 1946–1948 to take remedial action at both the Tokyo Tribunal and the United Nations (where the ‘Nürnberg Principles’ were broached to this end). Two critical pieces from this decade are included (by Georg Schwarzenberger, and by Hans Kelsen, who advised the prosecution and was hardly representative) but many others are not. This despite the fact that the academic community’s international law- yers and political scientists – particularly those based in the United States, such as Edwin Borchard, George Finch, Leo Gross, Erich Hula, Hans Leonhardt, Max Radin and Franz Schick7 – raised reservations at the time. The resulting balance of the ma- terial representing this crucial period makes Mettraux’s volume feel very much the ‘official’ version. 6 International Military Tribunal, Trial of the Major War Criminals Before the International Military Tribunal (1947–1949) vol. 19, 399 (emphasis added). 7 Borchard, ‘The Impracticality of “Enforcing” Peace’ 55 Yale L J (1946) 966; Finch, ‘The Nuremberg Trial and International Law’, 41 AJIL (1947) 20; Gross, ‘The Criminality of Aggressive War’, 41 Am Polit Sci Rev (1947) 205; Hula, ‘Punishment for War Crimes’, 13 Soc Res (1946) 1; Leonhardt, ‘The Nuremberg Trial: A Legal Analysis’ 11 Rev Pol (1949) 449; Radin, ‘Justice at Nuremberg’, 24 Foreign Aff (1946) 369; Schick, ‘The Nuremberg Trial and the International Law of the Future’, 41 AJIL (1947) 770. a t N e w Y o rk U n ive rsity o n F e b ru a ry 1 , 2 0 1 1 e jil.o xfo rd jo u rn a ls.o rg D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://ejil.oxfordjournals.org/ Imperfect Justice at Nuremberg and Tokyo 1089 This is a shame because those inclined towards scepticism have much to tell us about the trial and the legal thinking that informed it. Their criticisms focused pre- dominantly on jurisdiction, retroactivity and selectivity – the last two now widely accepted as legitimate complaints against Nuremberg. These arguments could be described as forceful but limited in scope. The approach to retroactivity, for example, was narrowly conceived: while many cited the crimes against peace charge as being an ex post facto enactment, only a few also mentioned the equally newly minted crimes against humanity charge8 and almost none the conspiracy count, hitherto virtually unknown in international law.9 When considering crimes against peace, they often discussed nullum crimen sine lege but rarely its accompanying coda, nulla poena sine lege. And although they often talked of the retroactive prohibition of aggressive war, they rarely discussed retroactive individual responsibility – the exception being de- fence lawyer Hermann Jahrreiss, who used this argument in court.10 (The sceptics’ failure to pick up on this latter issue puzzled Robert Jackson, who later surmised that this was either because ‘they do not understand its implications, or . . . they approve abandonment of the old concept of absolute sovereignty’.)11 Of all the charges, it was crimes against peace that proved the most contentious. British and French officials had in 1944–1945 privately questioned the validity of the charge, and the following year, while the trial was in progress, academics began to publicly raise similar concerns. A lightning rod for this discussion was criminolo- gist Sheldon Glueck’s 1946 Harvard Law Review essay (reprinted in the anthology) and then book, The Nuremberg Trial and Aggressive War, which followed the prosecu- tion’s lead in arguing that inter alia the 1923 draft Treaty of Mutual Assistance, the 1924 Geneva Protocol, the 1927 Eighth League Assembly resolution and the 1928 Kellogg-Briand Pact could be ‘regarded as powerful evidence of the existence of a widely prevalent custom among civilized peoples sufficient to energize a juristic cli- mate favorable to the regarding of a war of aggression as . . . downright criminal’.12 The reviewers of Glueck’s book were not persuaded by this line. Where, they enquired, was the supporting evidence of state practice and opinio juris? As George Finch wrote, custom could not be judicially established ‘by placing interpretations upon the words of treaties which are refuted by the acts of the signatories in practice, [or] by citing unratified protocols or public and private resolutions of no legal effect’.13 Another criticism of the charges, and particularly crimes against peace, related to the Charter’s selective focus on ‘the major war criminals of the European Axis’.14 8 The French judge, Donnedieu de Vabres, makes this observation, however, in: ‘The Nuremberg Trial and the Modern Principles of International Criminal Law’ (1947), in Mettraux, at 227. 9 A later exception was Julius Stone, in: Legal Controls of International Conduct: A Treatise on the Dynamics of Disputes and War-Law (1954), at 361. 10 IMT, supra note 6, vol. 17, at 478. 11 Jackson, ‘Some Problems in Developing an International Legal System’, 22 Temple L Q (1948) 147, at 153. 12 Glueck, The Nuremberg Trial and Aggressive War (1946), at 34 (original emphasis). 13 Finch, Review of The Nuremberg Trial and Aggressive War by Sheldon Glueck, 41 AJIL (1947) 334, at 334. 14 The Charter of the International Military Tribunal (1945), in Mettraux (appendices), at 736. a t N e w Y o rk U n ive rsity o n F e b ru a ry 1 , 2 0 1 1 e jil.o xfo rd jo u rn a ls.o rg D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://ejil.oxfordjournals.org/ 1090 EJIL 21 (2010), 1085–1102 Shortly after the Judgment was handed down, the British alternate judge, Norman Birkett, while noting that the Charter did not apply to the Soviet Union, the United States or Britain, declared that, ‘If it continues to apply only to the enemy, then I think the verdict of history may be against Nuremberg.’15 While the Germans were being tried, the Charter formalized the Allies’ refusal to relinquish immunity for themselves for similar crimes. This was a sensitive point, and others associated with the bench and the prosecution – Herbert Wechsler, Telford Taylor and Bernard Meltzer – also raised their concerns about the problem of selectivity.16 As predicted, this issue did indeed tarnish Nuremberg’s legacy – and to a greater degree than did retroactivity or the specifics of the Allies’ wartime conduct (the pros- ecution felt extremely vulnerable to countercharges over the Molotov-Ribbentrop Pact of 1939 and Anglo-French plans to breach Norway’s neutrality in 1940). This invites the question: Why then did they decide to embark on a high-risk trial? One can only agree with Richard Falk, who wrote in 1995 that it was hard to understand ‘why sovereign states should have been ever willing to validate such a subversive idea as that of international criminal accountability of leaders for war crimes’, and that this validation only made sense ‘if the imposition of accountability is understood to be a particularly advantageous response to a given geopolitical challenge whose wider implications can be avoided’.17 3 Tensions at Work Retroactivity and selectivity aside, there is still a great deal more to be said about the problems implicit within the Nuremberg charges – a matter of some import, given the present appearance of similar charges on the roster of the International Criminal Court. The charge of crimes against peace, for example, proved to be problematic not only because of the aforementioned problems, but also because internal contradic- tions ultimately rendered it unsustainable. One contradiction relates to sovereignty: the charge reflected both the impulse to protect sovereignty (by punishing assaults on the existing world order) and the impulse to breach sovereignty, by making indi- vidual leaders – as distinct from states – directly accountable to international law.18 Another tension relates to enforceability: as David Luban argued in his 1987 piece, reprinted in the anthology, the charge of crimes against peace simultaneously crimi- nalized aggression and ‘any attempt to enforce itself’ by taking action against threats 15 Birkett, ‘International Legal Theories Evolved at Nuremberg’ (1947), in Mettraux, at 307. 16 Wechsler, ‘The Issues of the Nuremberg Trial’ (1947), in Mettraux, at 319; T. Taylor, Nuremberg and Vietnam: An American Tragedy (1971), at 82; Meltzer, ‘A Note on Some Aspects of the Nuremberg Debate’, 14 U Chi L Rev (1947) 455, at 469. 17 Falk, ‘Telford Taylor and the Legacy of Nuremberg’, 37 Colum J Transnat’l L (1999) 693, at 710 (original emphasis). 18 K. Sellars, ‘Crimes Against Peace’ and International Law (PhD thesis) (2009), at 310. a t N e w Y o rk U n ive rsity o n F e b ru a ry 1 , 2 0 1 1 e jil.o xfo rd jo u rn a ls.o rg D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://ejil.oxfordjournals.org/ Imperfect Justice at Nuremberg and Tokyo 1091 to the global order. In consequence, the charge ‘cuts its own throat as an instrument of international peace’.19 One of the volume’s strengths is that it includes translations of half a dozen pieces that have hitherto been unavailable in English. The most notable of these is by the French judge Henri Donnedieu de Vabres, who in 1947 took issue with the conspiracy charge because it ‘gives to the Hitlerian enterprise the cover of a romantic prestige’.20 Half a century later the German legal philosopher Reinhard Merkel expertly dissected some of the problems associated with the court’s jurisdiction.21 And in the same decade a Russian writer, referred to in different parts of the anthology as ‘A.M. Larin’ and ‘Larin A.M. Prigovor’, addressed the often-overlooked subject of the Tribunal’s finding of facts.22 A telling aspect of this collection is that it reveals some of the writers’ misconcep- tions and occasional misrepresentations concerning the Allies’ respective roles in the establishment of the Tribunal. It is worth observing, for example, that the Soviets were not in favour of shooting the Nazi leaders (as Otto Kranzbühler stated)23 although Churchill was. Nor was Roosevelt a consistent advocate of a trial (as Robert Jackson claimed);24 he in fact wavered between legal and political solutions. The trial was not wholly ‘a brainchild of the Americans’ (as Luban stated)25 for the Soviets had con- ceived similar ideas. And the Russians did not join the trial reluctantly (as Jackson well knew)26 but firmly supported it as a judicial settling of accounts. To underscore this last point, it was no less a figure than Andrei Vishinsky, chief prosecutor at the 1930s Moscow trials, who in 1945 assumed responsibility for the Soviet team at Nuremberg. As previously noted, interpretations of Nuremberg have changed over the years. In the two decades immediately following the trial, the verdict tended to be negative. If aspects of the trial were not dismissed as misconceived or misdirected, then they were condemned as insufficient – the Eichmann trial, for example, was seen as making up for Nuremberg’s shortcomings on the Holocaust. Today the verdict tends to be more positive, and Guénaël Mettraux, like many others, inclines towards a less critical view, as reflected in his selection. No anthology can be complete, and any selection will inev- itably be criticized for this or that omission. In the end Mettraux has drawn together a valuable collection of commentaries into a single volume, which thoroughly deserves to become a standard reference work on the trial. 19 Luban, ‘The Legacies of Nuremberg’ (1987), in Mettraux, at 658. 20 Donnedieu de Vabres, supra note 8, at 243. 21 Merkel, ‘The Law of the Nuremberg Trial: Valid, Dubious, Outdated’ (1996), in Mettraux, at 566. 22 ‘Larin’, ‘Nuremberg Trial: The Law Against War and Fascism’ (1995), in Mettraux, 546–554. 23 Kranzbühler, ‘Nuremberg Eighteen Years Afterwards’ (1965), in Mettraux, at 444. 24 Jackson, ‘Introduction’ (1954), in Mettraux, at 701. 25 Luban, supra note 19, at 646. 26 Jackson, supra note 24. a t N e w Y o rk U n ive rsity o n F e b ru a ry 1 , 2 0 1 1 e jil.o xfo rd jo u rn a ls.o rg D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://ejil.oxfordjournals.org/ 1092 EJIL 21 (2010), 1085–1102 4 Trying War at Tokyo While the Nuremberg Tribunal has been the subject of a deluge of literature from all quarters since its inception, its less well-known sibling at Tokyo has not attracted a great deal of scholarly attention outside Japan. Two recent books go some way to- wards rectifying this situation. The British-based academic lawyers Neil Boister and Robert Cryer tell the ‘law story’,27 focusing on the charges, conduct and conclusions of the trial, while the American-based historian Yuma Totani concentrates on the court’s establishment and findings, and the response in Japan after the event. Although they reach different conclusions about the standing of the trial, the two books complement (and occasionally compensate for) one another. The International Military Tribunal for the Far East opened on 3 May 1946 in the highly symbolic location of the auditorium of the former Imperial Army Officers’ School in Tokyo. Here, the prosecutors would face all the problems experienced by their Nuremberg counterparts, and more besides. One of the greatest of these difficul- ties related to the character of the Second World War itself. From the outset, the Allies had justified the prosecution of the leaders of the Axis powers on the grounds that the conflict had been unique in the annals of warfare because of its totality and barbarity. This argument rested primarily upon a singular event: the Holocaust. Although the judges at Nuremberg declared crimes against peace to be the ‘supreme international crime’,28 it was in fact the existence of the death camps that formed the moral core of the Allies’ case against the Nazi leaders. The Second World War was therefore regarded as an exceptional event requiring special legal remedies, its singularity deriving from Germany’s actions. Japan’s pol- icies, by contrast, were unexceptional. Its leaders had certainly presided over whole- sale assaults and terrible atrocities, but they had not broken the mould of international politics by instituting policies to systematically annihilate entire national, ethnic, ra- cial or religious groups. As Bruno Simma noted in 1999: ‘Auschwitz was singularly German, and none of the offences committed by the Japanese political and military leaders came even close.’29 One silent casualty at Tokyo of this mismatch between German and Japanese crimes was the charge of crimes against humanity, which had initially been framed to address German crimes against Axis populations. Although the crime was listed in the Tokyo Charter along with crimes against peace and war crimes, it was mentioned just once in the Indictment, and only in passing in the majority Judgment. None of the books under review probe the reasons for its disappearance, but the decisive fac- tors must have been the Allies’ tacit recognition that nothing committed by Japan could compare to German crimes, combined with their reluctance to continue deploy- ing this sovereignty-piercing instrument. Even though the war crimes and murder 27 Boister and Cryer, at 328. 28 IMT, supra note 6, vol. 1, at 186. 29 Simma, ‘The Impact of Nuremberg and Tokyo: Attempts at a Comparison’, in A. Nisuke (ed.) Japan and International Law: Past, Present and Future (1999), at 83. a t N e w Y o rk U n ive rsity o n F e b ru a ry 1 , 2 0 1 1 e jil.o xfo rd jo u rn a ls.o rg D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://ejil.oxfordjournals.org/ Imperfect Justice at Nuremberg and Tokyo 1093 charges partly covered the same ground as crimes against humanity, many victims, such as the ‘comfort women’ from Japan’s colonies of Korea and Formosa, were left to seek justice by different means. 5 A Tarnished Reputation To date, history’s verdict on Tokyo has not been favourable. In 1948, a British Foreign Office official declared it to be a ‘political failure’,30 and since then, it has often been deemed a legal failure as well: Cherif Bassiouni, for example, described it as a prece- dent which legal history can only consider ‘with a view not to repeat it’.31 Neil Boister and Robert Cryer, however, set themselves the task of reassessing the legal issues aris- ing from the trial, and they do so to good effect. They did not have a great deal of sec- ondary literature to draw from. The contemporaneous legal coverage of the trial was remarkably thin, with only a score of articles, mostly short laudatory pieces written by prosecutors, appearing in English-language law journals. And since then, although there have been some notable additions to the literature by historians and political scientists, there has not been much from the legal profession (an exception being the works of the Dutch jurists, Cornelus Pompe and Bernard Röling).32 The authors thus draw a good deal of their illustrative material from the trial transcript and the papers of the Australian and New Zealand judges. In approaching the Tribunal, Boister and Cryer are scrupulously even-handed, acknowledging the problems associated with mounting an international trial, and giving the Tribunal credit for its clarification of the law on issues such as civilian com- mand responsibility. This, along with their meticulous analysis of the material, makes the criticisms that they do offer all the more devastating. In summary, they conclude that the prosecuting powers at Tokyo violated the principle of legality by creating the new charge of crimes against peace,33 treated the war crimes charges as almost an afterthought,34 and breached the undertaking to give the accused a fair trial.35 Not surprisingly, they reserve their sharpest criticisms for the conspiracy charges. Tokyo placed far greater stress on conspiracy than did Nuremberg, prompting Corn- elus Pompe to note in 1953 that it seemed as though the Tribunal ‘did not consider it so much its task to attribute responsibility for acts committed in international life, as to disclose the existence of a criminal design directed towards such acts’.36 This emphasis 30 National Archives (UK), FO 371/69834: Scott, 23/12/48. 31 Boister and Cryer, at 302. 32 C. A. Pompe, Aggressive War: An International Crime (1953); Röling, ‘The Nuremberg and the Tokyo Tri- als in Retrospect’, in Mettraux, 455–472; B.V.A. Röling and A. Cassese (ed), The Tokyo Trial and Beyond: Reflections of a Peacemonger (1993). 33 Boister and Cryer, at 136–137. 34 Ibid., at 175. 35 Ibid., at 102. 36 Pompe, supra note 32, at 27. a t N e w Y o rk U n ive rsity o n F e b ru a ry 1 , 2 0 1 1 e jil.o xfo rd jo u rn a ls.o rg D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://ejil.oxfordjournals.org/ 1094 EJIL 21 (2010), 1085–1102 arose because the lack of evidence linking defendants to specific events necessitated an indirect approach: first establishing an individual’s connection to the conspiracy, and then using membership of the conspiracy to signal personal responsibility for substant- ive crimes. Conspiracy was appealing because it provided a conceptual framework for the consideration of discrete policies and a diverse group of defendants, but it worked only if it could be proved that every defendant had played their allotted part in the grand plan. As Boister and Cryer note, certain individuals (such as Hirota Koki in the 1930s) were like ‘the poles holding up the tent’ – if one pole were to be removed, the tent would fall down.37 Despite the obvious problems, the majority of judges were preoccupied with sus- taining a conspiracy-led narrative even when considering the substantive crimes. As David Cohen noted in 1999, this drift from the individual to the collective occurred, for example, in a chapter of the majority Judgment on crimes against peace, which began by stating that the most important task was to ‘assess the responsibility of indi- viduals for these attacks’, and ended with reference to a collective entity: ‘the con- spirators’.38 He further observed that it neither set out plain standards of responsibility nor stated the findings on which individual verdicts were based.39 Although criminal guilt is personal, Boister and Cryer demonstrate that at times the Tribunal displayed a ‘cavalier approach to individual liability’.40 6 Contending Legal Philosophies With so many contentious issues up for discussion, it was perhaps inevitable that the Tokyo Tribunal would become a catalyst for debate about the future of international law – an issue addressed in Boister and Cryer’s chapter on the legal philosophy of the trial. As they note, both naturalists and positivists made their views known, with the American chief prosecutor Joseph Keenan later claiming (with characteristic hyper- bole) that the trial ‘served as a cockpit for a death struggle between two completely irreconcilable and opposed types of legal thinking’.41 And as at Nuremberg, crimes against peace generated the most heat. Positivists maintained that because aggres- sive warfare had not been criminalized before the Second World War, individuals could not be prosecuted for initiating it. Naturalists, on the other hand, argued that the principle of individual responsibility for aggression was generated spontaneously from public conscience, which would harden into law through its application to cases such as those at Tokyo. The authors pick their way through these and other con- troversies, showing, for example, that the better-known judges Radhabinod Pal and 37 Boister and Cryer, at 219. 38 Cohen, ‘Beyond Nuremberg: Individual Responsibility for War Crimes’, in C. Hesse and R. Post (eds), Hu- man Rights in Political Transitions: Gettysburg to Bosnia (1999), at 60–61. 39 Ibid., at 64. 40 Boister and Cryer, at 245. 41 J. B. Keenan and B. F. Brown, Crimes Against International Law (1950), at 13. a t N e w Y o rk U n ive rsity o n F e b ru a ry 1 , 2 0 1 1 e jil.o xfo rd jo u rn a ls.o rg D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://ejil.oxfordjournals.org/ Imperfect Justice at Nuremberg and Tokyo 1095 Bernard Röling were not as immaculately positivist as is often assumed. At the same time they take issue with Judith Shklar’s incisive but imperfect essay Legalism (1964), which touched on the intellectual traditions that underpinned the Tokyo Tribunal, and correct her assumption that the Japanese did not comprehend the Judeo-Chris- tian or naturalist themes manifested there.42 One of the most outspoken protagonists in these debates at the Tribunal was the aforementioned Joseph Keenan, an avowed naturalist with a conception of inter- national law which might be summarized as innovation in the service of orthodoxy. In his view, the law was a dynamic force, ultimately derived from God and directed towards the maintenance of the status quo. He believed that pre-war international arrangements had come about because some nations, by virtue of their superior cul- ture, had assumed control of others for the benefit of all. The only way for a country to lawfully alter these arrangements was by slow, evolutionary means, and Japan’s sud- den and violent intervention had in his view overturned a legitimate and moral world order. Such aggression had to be stopped because: ‘If Japan had the right to change its geographical and economic status suddenly by war, then every other nation as badly situated, from the economic standpoint, had the same right.’43 Armed with this idea, Keenan set out the case for the prosecution of aggression based upon the concept of unjust wars (that disrupted the status quo) and just wars (that restored the status quo). ‘The nucleus of crimes against peace is the criminally unjust war,’ he wrote, which was ‘always evil per se in the moral sphere and unjust in the judicial, despite the absence of positive legal undertakings to that effect.’44 In his view, it was necessary to use the trial to advance international law in order to pre- vent further unjust wars. Indeed, he was quite prepared to assert this transcendent aim over the apparently lesser task of administering justice: not only did he declare that he had ‘no particular interest in any individual or his punishment’ because the defendants were mere representatives of ‘a class and group’,45 but he rebuked defence lawyers for being willing to ‘sacrifice the common international good’ to secure the defendants’ interests.46 7 Pal’s Perspectives The most forthright opponent of Keenan’s approach was the Indian judge, Radhabinod Pal, whose dissent famously absolved all the Japanese defendants of all guilt. His stance, which was articulated just as third-worldist sentiment was beginning to stir, provides a revealing counterpoint to Keenan on the relationship between inter- national law and the status quo. Starting out from a strictly positivist position, he 42 Boister and Cryer, at 294–296. 43 Keenan and Brown, supra note 41, at 63. 44 Ibid., at 57 and 79. 45 Ibid., at 463. 46 Ibid., at 156. a t N e w Y o rk U n ive rsity o n F e b ru a ry 1 , 2 0 1 1 e jil.o xfo rd jo u rn a ls.o rg D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://ejil.oxfordjournals.org/ 1096 EJIL 21 (2010), 1085–1102 argued that it was perilous to innovate in line with the dictates of conscience because only adherence to the letter of the law, not ‘the “general moral sense” of humanity’,47 guaranteed predictability. The naturalist alternative, with its premature claims to uni- versalism, emitted (and here he quoted Lon Fuller) the ‘rich, deep odor of the witches’ cauldron’.48 Yet as Boister and Cryer note, Pal’s legal philosophy was more complex and accommodating than such words suggest.49 His suspicion concerning subject- ivity was linked to his doubts about the motives of the prosecuting powers, yet his attempt to posit an alternative worldview led him back towards a naturalist position. Addressing crimes against peace, Pal recalled the prosecuting powers’ history of violence in Asia, and warned that they might deploy the charge for their own self-interested reasons, such as maintaining ‘the very status quo which might have been organized and hitherto maintained only by force by pure opportunist “Have and Holders”.’50 He noted, for instance, Robert Jackson’s statement at Nuremberg that ‘whatever grievances a nation may have, however objectionable it finds the status quo, aggressive warfare is an illegal means for settling those grievances or for altering those conditions’.51 In other words, Jackson was effectively calling for the freezing of international relations – just or unjust – at the conclusion of the Second World War. Thereafter, the struggle against colonialism and exercise of ‘self-help by force’52 would be prohibited. For Pal, this restraint was unacceptable, for the colonized ‘cannot be made to submit to eternal domination only in the name of peace’.53 When taking issue with Jackson, Pal proposed a radical inversion of global prior- ities, with anti-colonial justice taking precedence over peace rather than peace taking precedence over justice (the latter being in his opinion the premise for the concept of crimes against peace). He thus departed from his positivist position and moved to- wards ‘just war’ theory – in the process stepping onto the same naturalist terrain as Keenan. Their immediate disagreement turned on the question: Were Japan’s wars unjust? Not according to Pal, for Japan’s leaders had believed that they were acting in self-defence. This was a substantial concession to the idea embedded within crimes against peace that wars could be categorized as either illegitimate (aggression) or le- gitimate (self-defence or sanction). Instead of rejecting this polarity, as an orthodox positivist might have done, Pal submitted to it, by attempting to shift Japan’s wars from the ‘aggressive’ to the ‘defensive’ side of the scale. Instead of reframing the de- bate, he found himself trapped within it. 47 R. Pal, International Military Tribunal for the Far East: Dissentient Judgment of Justice R.B. Pal (1953), at 112. 48 Boister and Cryer, at 286. 49 Ibid, at 286–291. 50 Pal, supra note 47, at 115. 51 IMT, supra note 6, vol. 2, at 149. 52 Pal, supra note 47, at 114. 53 Ibid., at 115. a t N e w Y o rk U n ive rsity o n F e b ru a ry 1 , 2 0 1 1 e jil.o xfo rd jo u rn a ls.o rg D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://ejil.oxfordjournals.org/ Imperfect Justice at Nuremberg and Tokyo 1097 8 Reinforcing Nuremberg Boister and Cryer have produced an illuminating account, and if there is any weak- ness, it relates not to their interpretation of the legal issues arising from the trial but from their failure to fully explain Tokyo’s role in relation to Nuremberg. By the time the Tokyo Tribunal opened, the Nuremberg Charter and Indictment had already been subjected to critical scrutiny by jurists and others, and found wanting on legal grounds, especially with respect to crimes against peace. The prosecuting powers were well aware that this charge had broken new ground, and hoped that the Tokyo Judgment would confirm Nuremberg’s determinations on aggressive war, thereby settling the debate.54 As a consequence, every possible measure was taken to ensure that Tokyo backed Nuremberg over this problematic charge, from the drafting of the Tokyo Indictment, which attempted to reinforce the crimes against peace charge with the conspiracy and murder charges, to the attempts before and during the trial to focus on aggression to the exclusion of the other substantive charges. These efforts were seen as highly im- portant because, as the British Foreign Office’s legal advisor Eric Beckett minuted, a failure to win the case on crimes against peace in Japan ‘would inter alia mean that the Tokyo Tribunal was saying that the Judgment of the Nuremberg Tribunal was based at any rate in part upon bad law’.55 The judges in Japan were thus bound by the dual obligation to uphold both the Tokyo Charter and the Nuremberg Judgment. The compulsion to defer to Nurem- berg was never publicly stated, of course, although as soon as it became clear to the Allies that the Tokyo bench had split over the question of the validity of crimes against peace, officials either privately sounded out the judges over schemes designed to en- sure that the judgment echoed the Nuremberg line (as the British did with Lord Pat- rick)56 or pressured them to abandon their disagreements with crimes against peace (as the Dutch did with Bernard Röling).57 The prosecuting powers’ determination to prop up Nuremberg therefore undermined the Tokyo judges’ autonomy, and inflamed the tensions that already existed on the bench. As it turned out, the will of the majority in favour of supporting Nuremberg prevailed, and the Tokyo Judgment duly duplicated the previous Judgment’s pro- nouncements on international law. (The only important exception was the Nuremberg ruling that individuals had international duties that transcended obligations to the state, which was dropped at Tokyo on the insistence of the Soviet judge, I.M. Zaryanov.) As the majority explained: ‘this Tribunal prefers to express its unqualified adherence 54 This theme is examined in greater detail in Sellars, ‘Lord Patrick and “Crimes Against Peace” at the Tokyo Tribunal, 1946–48’, Edinburgh L Rev (forthcoming). 55 National Archives (UK), FO 371/66552: Beckett, 5/5/47. 56 Sellars, supra note 54. 57 L. van Poelgeest, ‘The Netherlands and the Tokyo Tribunal’, Aspects of the Allied Occupation of Japan, Part II, Suntory-Toyota International Centre for Economics and Related Disciplines, London (1991), at 38–39. a t N e w Y o rk U n ive rsity o n F e b ru a ry 1 , 2 0 1 1 e jil.o xfo rd jo u rn a ls.o rg D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://ejil.oxfordjournals.org/ 1098 EJIL 21 (2010), 1085–1102 to the relevant opinions of the Nuremberg Tribunal rather than by reasoning the mat- ters anew in somewhat different language’ for this would ‘open the door to contro- versy by way of conflicting interpretations of the two statements of opinions’.58 9 One Trial, Many Views What then is the legacy of the Tokyo Tribunal? Just as Nuremberg was interpreted in new ways by successive generations of observers in the West, so Tokyo was inter- preted in new ways by successive generations in Japan. The historian Yuma Totani is primarily interested in the court’s findings and the subsequent Japanese response to them. In her vividly detailed book, she seeks to reclaim the Tribunal from its many and varied critics by clearing away some of the misapprehensions and prejudices that have taken root over the years. In the process, she arrives at a more favourable assess- ment of the trial than many others, including Boister and Cryer, have done. She begins by surveying the Allies’ preparation of the trial, the selection of sus- pects, and the question of the indictment of the Emperor Shōwa. Then she assesses the handling of leadership responsibility for atrocities, and the cases of the Rape of Nanking, the Burma-Siam ‘Death Railway’ and other mass crimes committed during the Asian-Pacific War. Of particular interest, though, is her comprehensive descrip- tion of the legacy of the trial in Japan, which has not been widely discussed in the literature about the Tribunal.59 She identifies three successive approaches taken by commentators over the years: the legal academics who in the late 1940s upheld the Tribunal as a necessary advance in the law; the conservative nationalists who from the early 1950s denounced it as victors’ justice; and the radical historians who from the early 1980s criticized it for its expedient narrative of the Asian-Pacific War. As Totani recounts, the first published analyses of the trial started to appear while the court was still sitting, and they were generally positive. From Tokyo University’s law faculty, for example, Dandō Shigemitsu argued in his 1946 article, ‘Sensō hanzai no rironteki kaibō’ (‘The Theoretical Anatomy of War Crimes’) that the criminaliza- tion of aggression had long been a principle of international law, and the ban on ex post facto enactments was anyway designed to protect the victims, not the manipulators, of arbitrary state power.60 The following year, his colleague Yokota Kisaburō contended in his book, Sensō hanzai ron (A Treatise on War Crimes) that international law was in 58 International Military Tribunal for the Far East [R John Pritchard (ed)], The Tokyo Major War Crimes Trial (1998), vol. 101, at 48439. 59 The issue is raised in some of the more general literature, however, such as Ian Buruma’s The Wages of Guilt: Memories of War in Japan and Germany (1995). 60 Totani, at 193. a t N e w Y o rk U n ive rsity o n F e b ru a ry 1 , 2 0 1 1 e jil.o xfo rd jo u rn a ls.o rg D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://ejil.oxfordjournals.org/ Imperfect Justice at Nuremberg and Tokyo 1099 a period of revolutionary change in which the concept of war crimes had expanded to embrace aggression – a crime which had clearly been committed by Japan because it had ‘ignored treaties, flouted justice’.61 It is worth noting that Totani’s chronological distinction between the first favour- able generation of analysts and second antipathetic generation is somewhat artificial, for the two outlooks must surely have co-existed from the start – it was just that early critics of the trial were silenced by Douglas MacArthur’s administration’s purges and censorship during the postwar Occupation.62 Only after April 1952, with the com- ing into force of the peace treaty and the lifting of the American restrictions, did the conservative lawyers and politicians begin to broadcast their views. They would make up for lost time by dominating the debate over the following decades. 10 The Nationalist Riposte Totani indicates that the first book setting out a nationalist ‘victors’ justice’ critique of the trial, Tōkyō saiban o sabaku (Judging the Tokyo Trial), was published in 1953. Its author, Takigawa Masajirō, formerly Tokyo defendant Shimada Shigetarō’s lawyer, argued that far from being the self-proclaimed exemplar of civilized values, the Tri- bunal was in reality an instrument for inculcating defeatism in the Japanese people.63 Moreover, he wrote, the severity of the sentences handed down at Tokyo compared to Nuremberg could be put down to racial prejudice: ‘the Japanese are coloured and the Germans white’.64 Other books expressing similar sentiments appeared later. The 1961 memoir, Tōkyō saiban no shōtai (The True Character of the Tokyo Trial) by Sugawara Yutaka, Araki Sadao’s lawyer, claimed that the Allies handed down seven death sen- tences to settle scores over seven wartime actions – Pearl Harbor, Singapore, Bataan and so on.65 And the 1966 memoir, Hiroku: Tōkyō saiban (The Secret Record About the Tokyo Trial) by Kiyose Ichirō, Tōjō Hideki’s lawyer, claimed that the war crimes charges brought at the trial were an invalid pretext for the harsh punishments of the accused.66 The conservative critics were more interested in justifying Japanese policies than in analysing the nuances of international law, although as Totani explains, they were happy to use Radhabinod Pal’s dissent to vindicate their stance and invest their arguments with legal credibility.67 Moreover, she shows that Pal himself was complicit in this process, as his sympathy with defence arguments ripened into support for 61 Ibid., at 196. 62 Mayo, ‘Civil Censorship and Media Control in Early Occupied Japan: From Minimum to Stringent Sur- veillance’ in Robert Wolfe (ed.) Americans as Proconsuls: United States Military Government in Germany and Japan, 1944–1952 (1984), at 297–298, 310, 318-319. 63 Totani, at 230. 64 ‘Tokyo War Crimes Trial Farce; Japanese Lawyer’, Japan News, 12/9/53. 65 Totani, at 230–231. 66 Ibid., at 231. 67 Ibid., at 224. a t N e w Y o rk U n ive rsity o n F e b ru a ry 1 , 2 0 1 1 e jil.o xfo rd jo u rn a ls.o rg D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://ejil.oxfordjournals.org/ 1100 EJIL 21 (2010), 1085–1102 the defendants’ cause. He visited Japan on three occasions after the trial – in 1952, 1953 and 1966 – addressing rapturous nationalist audiences, sipping tea with the defendants’ families, and visiting the inmates of Sugamo Prison. Although Totani is interested only in his relations with the Japanese right, both Elizabeth Kopleman and Boister and Cryer have noted the multi-faceted character of his legal and political phil- osophy.68 This is why during the Cold War decades Pal found common ground with Japanese nationalists over pan-Asianism and anti-communism, with the non-aligned movement over anti-colonialism and self-determination, and with Western anti- militarists over American foreign policies – and was lionized by them all. 11 New Forms of Victors’ Justice In the early 1980s Pal’s dissentient legacy began to fade, and a new wave of pro- gressive Japanese historians sought to move beyond the good trial/bad trial argu- ment. Totani observes that this generation, armed with newly declassified documents and mindful of Japan’s growing assertiveness in Southeast Asia, concluded that the problem with the Tokyo trial was not that it went too far, but that it did not go far enough.69 Led by their doyen Awaya Kentarō, they criticized the prosecuting powers for ignoring their own crimes of Hiroshima and Nagasaki and for selecting Japan’s crimes in line with their own concerns – concentrating, for example, on the experi- ence of whites rather than Asians, failing to indict the Emperor Shōwa, and ignoring Unit 731’s bacteriological experiments. They argued that the trial had been driven by political expediency in furtherance of a status quo imposed by the United States and the colonial powers in East Asia and the Pacific, and therefore it was victors’ justice, albeit of a different variety than that identified by the nationalists. As such, it hindered Japan’s ability to face up to its own past. This more radical reading of the trial was guided by modern assumptions about the Allies’ prejudices which, as Totani skilfully shows, were sometimes misplaced. She disputes the view that prosecutors, driven by racism and non-legal priorities, paid little heed to Asian victims. She argues that they did focus on the Asian experience, and for good reason: the colonial powers wished to re-establish their shaky credibility in recently reclaimed colonies by making common cause with the colonized.70 Fur- thermore, she notes that contrary to claims of gender prejudice, the prosecutors did pay attention to the sexual violence perpetrated against Asian women, especially in China and the Dutch East Indies, although they failed to convince the judges that such actions were the outcome of the defendants’ orders from on high.71 Her argument breaks down, however, when she takes issue with the idea that the trial was a manifestation of victors’ justice, designed to sustain American and 68 Kopelman, ‘Ideology and International Law: The Dissent of the Indian Justice at the Tokyo War Crimes Trial’ 23 NYU J Int’l Law & Pol (1991) 373, at 375–376; Boister and Cryer, at 286–291. 69 Totani, at 250. 70 Ibid., at 162–163. 71 Ibid., at 178–179, 185. a t N e w Y o rk U n ive rsity o n F e b ru a ry 1 , 2 0 1 1 e jil.o xfo rd jo u rn a ls.o rg D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://ejil.oxfordjournals.org/ Imperfect Justice at Nuremberg and Tokyo 1101 colonial interests in Asia. Leaving aside her preoccupation with Japan’s perception of itself as a nation either traduced or suborned by the Allies, one must conclude that any trial conducted after a war is de facto victors’ justice. Indeed, several contributors to Mettraux’s anthology make precisely this point. ‘In the existing state of international law it is probably unavoidable that the right of punishing war criminals should be uni- laterally assumed by the victor,’ wrote Hersch Lauterpacht in 1944.72 David Luban further argued that, because the crimes against peace charge criminalised efforts to enforce itself, leaders could only be prosecuted once they had embarked on and been beaten in an aggressive war, and that consequently, ‘Only victors’ justice is possible.’73 12 Tests of History In the course of challenging some of the negative misapprehensions about the Tokyo Tribunal, Totani reaches for more positive interpretations than its legacy has thus far allowed. The material she presents, however, tends to undermine her assertions. So she maintains, for example, that the trial ‘marked the starting point of Japan’s con- frontation with its past’,74 but then chronicles the perennial objections relating to the court, the charges, and the prosecution’s evidence – all of which prove that the Tri- bunal failed in its didactic function. She further states that the trial’s findings estab- lished the chronological and geographical framework of the postwar ‘historiography of World War II’,75 and then undercuts this position by describing the persistent focus in Japan on the absences in the Tribunal’s narrative: the unmentioned Allied crimes, the unaddressed Japanese crimes, the un-indicted Emperor. As the presiding judge William Webb cautioned at the time: ‘A Judgment may itself be historic, yet its con- tents may be incomplete as history’76 – all too incomplete, the critics thought. Continuing in a positive vein, Totani maintains that despite the mishandling of the conspiracy counts, the Tribunal’s findings on the substantive counts have ‘stood up to the test of history’.77 While no serious impartial commentator has contested the find- ings on war crimes, the same cannot be said of the findings on crimes against peace, which are still the subject of debate. This interrogative process began as early as May 1948, when the French judge Henri Bernard complained that a draft of the Judgment contained tendentious readings of Russo-Japanese relations, offered an opinion on Japan and the Hague Convention that had not been proved, and raised Japan’s Open Door policy in China despite discussion of it being barred in court.78 The passages to which he objected appeared in the majority’s Judgment, and concerned matters 72 Lauterpacht, ‘The Law of Nations and the Punishment of War Crimes’ (1944), in Mettraux, at 14. 73 Luban, supra note 19, at 658. 74 Totani, at 2. 75 Ibid., at 97. 76 Boister and Cryer, at 312. 77 Totani, at 97. 78 Australian War Memorial, Webb papers, 3DRL 2481 Series 4/7/4: Bernard to Tribunal members, ‘Remarks Suggested by Draft of Judgment’, 10/5/48. a t N e w Y o rk U n ive rsity o n F e b ru a ry 1 , 2 0 1 1 e jil.o xfo rd jo u rn a ls.o rg D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://ejil.oxfordjournals.org/ 1102 EJIL 21 (2010), 1085–1102 which continue to exercise scholars to this day. Pronouncements on the tests of his- tory are in this instance premature. It is possible that Totani’s interesting and useful attempt to reconsider the trial’s reputation will herald a new generation of Japanese commentators. Inspired by developments in international criminal law, aware of Japan’s growing military obli- gations abroad, and keen to recast relations with their Chinese neighbour, they will have many motives for clearing away the political detritus that has accreted around the trial over the past six decades. But it is one thing to challenge misinterpretations, and quite another to attempt the rehabilitation of a deeply flawed enterprise. Tokyo was the very blackest of courtroom dramas, with an abundance of sombre lessons for jurists as well as for politicians and historians. It is to be hoped that future generations will pay heed to them. 13 In Conclusion These three books make a strong contribution to our understanding of the formation, conduct and outcome of the postwar tribunals, and offer important insights into some of the issues that are of practical relevance to the development of international crim- inal law today. Guénaël Mettraux has brought together many of the essential writ- ings about the Nuremberg Tribunal into a single volume; Yuma Totani has offered thought-provoking new perspectives on the Tokyo Tribunal; and Neil Boister and Robert Cryer have produced a nuanced analysis of the legal issues arising from that trial. Lawyers will find instructive material in them all. a t N e w Y o rk U n ive rsity o n F e b ru a ry 1 , 2 0 1 1 e jil.o xfo rd jo u rn a ls.o rg D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://ejil.oxfordjournals.org/ work_4hsiral7jjhaxj25yxxs3ikfau ---- Originalni naučni rad Primljen: 9. 2. 2017. Revidirana verzija: 29. 3. 2017. Prihvaćen: 29. 3. 2017. UDK: 340.114 340.134 doi: 10.5937/nabepo22-13148 PROCEDURALNA PRAVDA, ISTINITOST I ISPRAVNOST1 Dragan M. Mitrović2 Pravni fakultet Univerziteta u Beogradu „Mora da je strašno verovati u neki autoritet kao istinu umesto u istinu kao jedini autoritet.“ Sažetak: Cilj ovog rada nije da podrži postojanje proceduralne pravde, za šta se zalažu najpoznatiji zagovornici shvatanja o po- stojanju proceduralne pravde (Dž. Rols i O. Hefe, a zatim L. Fuler, H. Hart, R. Dvorkin, P. Koler, M. Van den Bos i drugi), već da pro- ceduralnu pravdu razmotri iz ugla istinitosti i ispravnosti. Budući da se ne radi o istim već povezanim pojmovima, može se zaklju- čiti da se istinitost i ispravnost ne podudaraju, isto kao što se ne podudaraju pravda i pravo. Nešto što je istinito ne mora da bude ispravno. I obrnuto, nešto što je ispravno ne mora da bude istini- to. Očigledno, reč je odnosu cilja (istinitosti, pravde i pravičnosti) i sredstva (ispravnosti, korektnosti, preciznosti, pouzdanosti itd., rečju solidnosti). Razmatranje odnosa istinitosti i ispravnosti na primeru stvarno postojeće pravde i stvarno nepostojeće proceduralne pravde, po- kreće druga važna pitanja, npr. odnosa materijalnih (supstancijal- nih) i formalnih (proceduralnih) pravnih pravila, pravičnosti kao 1 Ovaj članak je rezultat rada na istraživačkom projektu Pravnog fakulteta Univerziteta u Beogradu za 2017. godinu pod nazivom „Identitetski preobražaj Srbije“ koji finansira Ministarstvo za nauku i tehnološki razvoj Republike Srbije.. 2 Dr Dragan M. Mitrović, redovni profesor Pravnog fakulteta Univerziteta u Beogradu, draganm@ius.bg.ac.rs Dragan Mitrović [2] NBP • Žurnal za kriminalistiku i pravo mesta susretanja pravde, prava i procedure itd. U još dubljoj senci nalazi se pitanje odnosa prirodnog i pozitivnog prava. Može se zaključiti da proceduralna pravda ne postoji. Ali, pravda postoji, samo ona nije proceduralna, što nije ni pravičnost. Pro- cedura je jedino ispravno sredstvo prava, ali pravo nije jedino ispravno sredstvo pravde. Ključne reči: pravda, pravičnost, istinitost, ispravnost, procedu- ralno pravo, proceduralna pravda. Uvod Pravda (iustitia) predstavlja vrhunsku društvenu i pravnu vrednost. Ona je vrednost zbog toga što je jedna vrsta srazmernosti i sklada, sve do postiza- nja harmonije, koja je drugi naziv za apsolutnu pravdu. Pored te apsolutne, božanske ili prirodne pravde, postoji i društvena pravda sa svojim izvedenim vrstama (moralna, religijska, pravna), koja je relativna u ljudskim razmerama.3 Posebnu vrstu predstavlja pravna pravda. Ona je važna vrsta društvene pravde jer se smatra sinonimom ili za srazmerno, ili za jednako. Određuje se prema dva formalna pravna obrasca, zbog čega se govori o dve vrste pravne pravde. Prva je distributivna pravda (iustitia distributiva: „svakome srazmer- no“), koja je prvobitna, položajna i nalaže da se „nejednako postupa s nejed- nakima“. Druga je komutativna (iustitia commutativa: „svakome jednako“), koja je razmenska i nalaže da se „jednako postupa s jednakima“. U najužem značenju, pravna pravda označava saobražavanje zakonu (zakonska pravda / iustitia legalis). Može se govoriti i o sudskoj pravdi (a ne samo o pravičnosti) kao posebnoj vrsti ispoljavanja pravde tamo gde su sudske presude izvori pra- va. Ali na pitanje u čemu se sastoji materijalna pravda, ne može se odgovoriti nikakvim sličnim obrascem, osim najstarijim, antičkim, da je pravedno služiti opštem dobru.4 Na primer, najnoviji pokušaji da se odredi solidarna pravda, po kojoj od zajedničkih dobara više treba dati slabim i siromašnim a manje ja- čim i bogatim (pravda Robina Huda), nisu obrasci materijalne pravde kakvim se predstavljaju, već Aristotelove distributivne pravde. A ona je formalna. Pravna pravda, budući da je vrsta društvene pravde, nije savršena. Ali to nije ni pravo. Zbog toga između nesavršene pravne pravde i još nesavršenijeg prava uvek postoji manja ili veća napetost.5 Pravdu je lakše osetiti nego odre- 3 Vid. P. Holbah, Sistem prirode, Beograd, 1950; Aristotel, Nikomahova etika, Beograd, 1970. 4 H. Kelzen, Elementi teorije pravnih normi. Pozni izabrani spisi, Beograd – Podgorica, 2003, str. 122. 5 T. Živanović, Sistem sintetičke filozofije prava, III, Beograd, 1959, str. 675–679. NBP • Journal of Criminalistics and Law [3] PROCEDURALNA PRAVDA, ISTINITOST I ISPRAVNOST diti ili postići, jer pravo nikad ne može da postane sama pravda. Zbog toga je svako pravo u određenoj meri nepravedno. Ali, ono ne sme da postane izopa- čeno i da ostvaruje krivdu. Imajući upravo to na umu, Ciceron (Marcus Tu- llius Cicero) odredio je svrhu prava kao veštinu prave mere pri podeli dobara među građanima (Sit ergo in iure civili finis hic legitimae atque usitatae in rebus causisque civium aequabilitatis conservatio). Time je osvežio stariju Platonovu i Aristotelovu ideju o postizanju opšteg dobra kao najvećeg postignuća mate- rijalne pravde. To znači da „normalno pravo“ mora sadržati barem „minimum pravde“, koja se preko opštih pravnih principa uliva u pravo (kako predlaže R. Dvorkin / R. Dworkin). Ali, ni takva pravda nije proceduralna.6 1. Rolsovo i Hefeovo shvatanje proceduralne pravde Budući da je od sredine prošlog veka obnovljeno a zatim i pojačano in- teresovanje za prirodnopravna istraživanja,7 sve češće je počelo da se govori o vrstama pravde: međunarodnoj, političkoj, korporativnoj, solidarnoj, orga- nizacionoj, transakcionoj, kompenzacionoj itd.,8 različitim od tradicionalnih oblika religijske, moralne i pravne pravde. Šta više, sve češće je počelo da se zagovara postojanje proceduralne pravde kao posebne vrste pravne pravde, pored zakonske i sudske pravde. Takvo zalaganje je prihvaćeno sa izvesnim olakšanjem u pozitivistički usmerenoj jurisprudenciji na Zapadu. Ono se može smatrati njenim zakasne- lim odgovorom na renesansu prirodnopravnih učenja u drugoj polovini XX veka. Neobično je da se za proceduralnu pravdu zalažu i pisci koji pripadaju suprotnoj orijentaciji. Takvo zalaganje se može smatrati neodmerenim odgo- vorom pripadnika prirodnopravne jurisprudencije. Ali, to olakšanje prvih i zalaganje drugih nije ni umesno ni korisno, jer proceduralna pravda ne po- stoji. Ona je samo jedan misaoni konstrukt (konstrukcija) i eksperiment u pravnoj filozofiji i teoriji. 6 Budući da glavna tema nije pravda, već njena izvedenica, tzv. proceduralna pravda, to o brojnim shvatanjima pravde dodatno vid. njihov pregled u Encyclopaedia Britanica. Ulti- mate 2014 Free Download. 7 Do toga je došlo zahvaljujući filozofsko-naučnom učinku G. Radbruha (Gustav Rad- bruch), izloženom pre svega u njegovom čuvenom delu Filozofija prava, a zatim je poja- čano u nemačkoj pravnoj filozofiji i anglosaksonskoj jurisprudenciji. Vid. G. Radbruh, Filozofija prava, Beograd, 1980 (2016). 8 Vid. R. T. Di Džordž, Poslovna etika, Beograd, 2003; R. Nozik, Anarhija, država, utopija, Zagreb, 2003; B. B. Sovilj, Put kroz pravo do pravde, Petrovaradin, 2004; Ž. Vučković, Bi- znis i moral, 2006; I. Kant, Zasnivanje metafizike morala, Beograd, 2008. Dragan Mitrović [4] NBP • Žurnal za kriminalistiku i pravo Najpoznatiji zagovornici učenja o postojanju proceduralne pravde su Džon Rols i Otfrid Hefe. Pored njih, i drugi pisci, pretežno anglosaksonski (L. Fuler / L. Fuller, H. Hart / H. Hart, R. Dvorkin, F. Hajek / F. Hayek i M. van den Bos / M. van den Bos) zagovaraju slično učenje. Kada je reč o učenju Džona Rolsa (John Rawls) o proceduralnoj pravdi, „princip otvorenosti položaja“, izložen u njegovom čuvenom delu Teorija prav- de,9 sadrži zamisao o idealnom početnom društvenom uslovu ili položaju kao i uverenje da „svi položaji“ pojedinaca u društvu nisu „otvoreni“ (iako neki ipak jesu). Ovo drugo, Rolsovo uverenje, pokazuje da pojedinci nisu jednaki čak ni u pogledu raspolaganja mogućnostima. Uostalom, poznato je da druš- tvena utakmica nikad nije nepristrasna i pravedna, jer je nameštena pre samog početka. Čak ni u Rusoovom idealizovanom opisu prirodnog stanja ljudskog roda „bez utakmice“ ne postoji takva sasvim „poštena“ jednakost − ljudi su različiti, a samim tim i nejednaki.10 Tu činjenicu, na koju je već ukazao Žan- Žak Ruso (Jean-Jacques Rousseau) govoreći o „plemenitim divljacima“, Rols prihvata kao očiglednu, ali uprkos tome, i dalje smatra odlučujućom svoju idealizovanu viziju nužne nepristrasnosti u pogledu „jednakosti mogućnosti“, a time i nužne ispravnosti pojedinaca u društvu. Naravno da takva nepristra- snost i ispravnost kod osvešćenih pojedinaca može da proizvede samo osećaj lične osujećenosti i nepravde.11 Takva „otvorenost položaja“, od koje Rols polazi govoreći o proceduralnoj pravdi, odnosi se i dalje prenosi na sve čisto proceduralne situacije u kojima pojedinci mogu da se nađu (od vrste i način korišćenja proceduralnih pravila prilikom određivanja početnog položaja pojedinca u društvu ili zaposlenog u preduzeća, sve do položaja okrivljenog ili svedoka u postupku pred sud- skim organima). Šta više, nepostojanje nužne nepristrasnosti u društvenom i pravnom smislu, kao i ishodeće ispravnosti u pogledu društvenog ponašanja i pravilne primene pravnih propisa12 (reči koje Rols pominje kao neku vrstu mantre) ne samo da pojedince lišavaju rezultata njihovih pregnuća već im oduzimaju mogućnost da dožive lično „iskustvo samoostvarenja“ koje je jed- no od nekoliko „glavnih oblika ljudskog dobra“ uopšte. Time Rols potvrđuje, možda nesvesno, opštu teodicejsku tragičnost ljudskog bića, jer sve što tvrdi ide u prilog zaključku suprotnom njegovim početnim postavkama. Ovaj svet se zbilja menja zbog uticaja podsticajnih i prihvatljivih ideja, ali ovom svetu same ideje i zamisli nisu dovoljne. Kada se razmotri Rolsovo shvatanje o proceduralnoj pravdi, može se za- paziti da se glavni nedostatak u njegovom učenju sastoji u tome što društvena 9 Dž. Rols, Teorija pravde, Beograd – Podgorica, 1998, str. 91. 10 Vid. Ž. Ž. Ruso, Rasprava o porijeklu i osnovama nejednakosti među ljudima, Zagreb, 1978. 11 Dž. Rols, Opus citatum, str. 93. 12 Ibidem, str. 92 i dalje. NBP • Journal of Criminalistics and Law [5] PROCEDURALNA PRAVDA, ISTINITOST I ISPRAVNOST i pravna pravila pomoću kojih određuje postavke i merila za uspostavljanje pojma proceduralne pravde (on) unapred proglašava proceduralnim iako ona to nisu. To su pre svih pravila kojima se određuje „princip otvorenosti polo- žaja“ kao i pravila koja utvrđuju način nepristrasnog i ispravnog sprovođenja proceduralnih normi, a ona su materijalna iako se odnose na način izvođenja procedure. Već ta činjenica pokazuje da je Rolsova glavna postavka, sadržana u njegovom „principu otvorenosti položaja“, virtuelna i fiktivna, kao i Kelze- nova „pranorma“. Ta postavka ne postoji i ne može se koristiti kao polazište za određivanje proceduralne pravde. Kao što je pomenuto, razlog je očigledan: „princip otvorenosti položaja“, kao i „princip nepristrasne mogućnosti“ (kao načina za postizanje) „jednakosti“, materijalnog je a ne proceduralnog karak- tera. Reč je o materijalnim pravilima koja određuju način na koji će se sprovo- diti čisto proceduralna društvena i pravna pravila. Isto se može reći i za Rolsove „nezavisne kriterijume“, tj. merila ili standar- de koji treba da uspostave proceduralnu pravdu.13 Ni oni nisu proceduralnog već materijalnog karaktera. Oni, čak, mogu da budu pravedni, ali ne kao sa- stojak proceduralne pravde. Treba naglasiti da takva jasna merila i standardi uopšte ne postoje − zbog čega nisu jasno određeni ni u Rolsovom učenju, niti postoji izvodljiva procedura koja neizostavno dovodi do ispravnog ishoda, tj. do proceduralne pravde. Ali sve to nije sprečilo Rolsa da ustvrdi kako ne- pristrasna procedura „prenosi“ svoju nepristrasnost na ispravan, tj. pravičan „ishod“. Dakle, opet je reč o njegovom uverenju da može da se ostvari proce- duralna pravda. Rols takođe tvrdi da više nije nužno voditi računa o beskrajno različitim okolnostima i stalnim promenama relativnih položaja određenih osoba, kao što je nekad činjeno u građanskim ugovorno-prirodnopravnim teorijama, jer je dovoljno da je sistem (državni, a naročito pravni) ispravno postavljen („strukturiran“). Kao da sistem može ono što priroda nije uspela. Tom prili- kom je zanemario da su Žan-Žak Ruso i Džon Lok (John Locke) mnogo pre njega uspostavljanje državnog sistema i sistema prava izvodili iz prirodnog i društvenog stanja, a ne prirodno i društveno stanje iz istog takvog državnog i pravnog sistema. Kao što je pomenuto, ni u tom konstruktu ili simulakrumu prvobitnog stanja, kao i kasnijeg društvenog stanja, pojedinci nisu jednaki.14 Umesto tog putokaza, Rols uslove (koje sam unapred postavlja) organizuje u veštački stvorenu virtuelnu zamisao „prvobitnog položaja“.15 Tvrdeći da je pogrešno usmeriti pažnju na promenljive relativne položaje pojedinaca i oče- kujući da svaka takva promena bude po sebi pravedna, Rols sam osporava vla- stitu početnu postavku i priznaje da je ona fiktivna, da je takođe reč o jednom 13 Ibidem. 14 Ibidem, str. 119 i dalje. 15 T. Glintić, Pogovor knjizi Dž. Rolsa Teorija pravde, str. 526−527. Dragan Mitrović [6] NBP • Žurnal za kriminalistiku i pravo konstruktu i simulakrumu. Slični problemi su svojevremeno prisilili Ronalda Dvorkina da razvije svoju političku teoriju prava, posle svoje pravne teorije (koja nije mogla da odgovori na vrhunska pravna pitanja koja je sebi stavio u zadatak da reši).16 Ni u ovoj drugoj, političkoj, Dvorkin takođe nije uspeo da pronađe merila i standarde za prelivanje prirodnog u pozitivno pravo. Umesto njih, uspeo je samo da izloži uputstva, a slično postupa i Rols kada govori o proceduralnoj pravdi. Rolsovo shvatanje „principa otvorenosti položaja“ i postojanja „nezavisnih kriterijuma“, očigledno, stvar je njegovog ličnog uverenja. Ali, to je slučaj i sa Rolsovim shvatanjem savršene i nesavršene proceduralne pravde. Jednostav- no, nije moguće odrediti postupak koji sigurno pruža željeni rezultat u smislu postizanja proceduralne pravde, pogotovo ne automatski. To priznaje i sam Rols, koji je u pravu kada kaže da savršena proceduralna pravda ne postoji, ali greši kada tvrdi suprotno za nesavršenu proceduralnu pravdu, jer procedural- na pravda uopšte ne postoji.17 I jedna i druga su himere. Pravda nije himera, ali nije ni proceduralna. Kada je reč o shvatanju Otfrida Hefea (Otfreid Höffe), koje je izloženo u njegovoj knjizi Pravda. Filozofski uvod,18 prvo treba primetiti da Hefe svoje izlaganje o proceduralnoj pravdi započinje tvrdnjom da su za pravno obavezu- juće odluke „neophodni definisani postupci“. To nije sporno, ali je sporno ne- što drugo: njegova tvrdnja da se ti postupci „zasnivaju na principima pravde“ (npr., kakve veze ima postupak za naplatu poreza od građana sa principima pravde?; ko to tvrdi, mora da prizna da je svaka država koja naplaćuje porez od svojih građana pravedna ili da barem počiva na principima pravde).19 Sporna je i sledeća Hefeova tvrdnja. On kaže: „Kada je reč o postupku, ne radi se neposredno o sadržajima ili rezultatima, već o nadležnostima, rokovi- ma i formama“ koje nisu same sebi svrha već „proizvode onu opštu spremnost da se prihvate odluke zakonodavca koje još nisu sadržinski određene“ (tu Hefe brka spremnost građana da imaju zakonodavca sa njihovom spremnošću da prihvate zakonodavčevu „mačku u džaku“, u obliku svakog budućeg zakona čiju sadržinu unapred ne mogu da upoznaju). I dalje, „postupci moraju biti otvoreni za potrebe i interese onih kojih se oni tiču“ (to samo u slučaju da su odnosni subjekti telepate kada je reč o budućim zakonima − naknadno upoznavanje sa takvim zakonima, kada su već doneti, štetno je za građane i opasno). Uz to, dodaje Hefe, sami postupci moraju biti „takvi da se mogu na- učiti“ (zašto i od koga?)... „i, pored toga, oni se moraju oslanjati na prethodne 16 Vid. R. Dvorkin, Carstvo prava, Beograd, 2003; Shvaćanje prava ozbiljno, Zagreb, 2003. 17 Vid. Dž. Rols, Opus citatum, str. 90−95. 18 Vid. O. Hefe, Pravda. Filozofski uvod, Novi Sad, 1998. O ovoj Hefeovoj knjizi vid. sa- držajan prikaz: I. Jovanov, Pravda. Filozofski uvod, Zbornik Pravnog fakulteta u Novom Sadu, br. 2/2014, str. 495−500. 19 O. Hefe, Opus citatum, str. 47. NBP • Journal of Criminalistics and Law [7] PROCEDURALNA PRAVDA, ISTINITOST I ISPRAVNOST datosti koje su, sa svoje strane, takođe pravedne − koje, u najmanju ruku, nisu nespojive sa supstancijalnom pravdom“ (?!).20 Zatim Hefe razlikuje tri vrste proceduralne pravde, za razliku od Rolsa koji se zadovoljava sa dve njihove vrste. Reč je o „čistoj“, „nesavršenoj“ i „savrše- noj“ proceduralnoj pravdi. Samo „čista“ proceduralna pravda predstavlja ne- što više od „puke supsidijarne legitimacije“, koju Hefe vezuje za „nesavršenu pravdu... koja preovlađuje u pravu i državi“. Propustio je da zapazi da je „nesa- vršena pravda“ od one vrste od koje je „gvožđe drveno“. Kako god bilo, čak ni Hefeova nesavršena pravda (za koju on sam priznaje da preovlađuje u pravu i državi) ne može da bude lišena ispravno vođenog postupka, nepristrasnosti itd.21 U protivnom, važila bi Ulpijanova (Domitius Ulpianus) izreka „Zakon važi jer tako hoće vladalac“ (Quod principi placuit, legis habet vigorem). Hefe tvrdi i da „čista“ pravda „leži u samom postupku, dok o kriterijumu za pravedan rezultat, koji bi bio nezavisan od postupka, ne može biti reči“.22 On time pojam pravde izvodi iz proceduralnih normi i tvrdi da se proceduralna pravda može izvesti iz sebe same, iz vlastitih merila koja ne mogu unapred da obezbede pravedan rezultat (što je njegov originalni „orobourus“). Na taj na- čin, on relativizira pravdu, kao i Majkl Volzer (Michael Voltzer), i dozvoljava da se pravednim smatra i ono što je nepravedno. Jedino Volzer pravdu izvodi iz promenljivosti društvenih uslova i odnosnog kulturnog miljea društva,23 dok Hefe to direktno čini iz proceduralnih pravila koja ne moraju da obezbe- de pravedan rezultat u obliku zakonske ili sudske pravde ili pravičnosti. Uz to, Hefe ne objašnjava zašto su proceduralna pravila uopšte pravedna, osim što ih on takvim smatra. Ako je uverenje argument u filozofiji, to nije slučaj u nauci. Druge dve vrste proceduralne pravde ostvaruju se „putem postupka“. Kod tzv. savršene proceduralne pravde „postoji neko nezavisno merilo za pravedan rezultat, kao i postupak kojim se taj rezultat ostvaruje sa približnom izvesno- šću“. Zatim Hefe daje primer jednake podele kolača, što se odnosi na komuta- tivnu a ne proceduralnu pravdu. Propustio je da zapazi da je za (komutativnu, a ne za proceduralnu) pravdu važno da su delovi jednaki, a ne na koji način i kojim sredstvom se kolač seče na jednake delove (što bi, valjda, trebalo da važi za nepostojeću proceduralnu pravdu).24 Takođe, Hefe tvrdi, kada je reč o „nesavršenoj proceduralnoj pravdi“, da i tada „za pravedan rezultat postoji jedan nezavisan kriterijum“. Njega Hefe ilustruje primerom iz krivičnog prava i tvrdi da je krivična proceduralna pravda postignuta kada su svi pravi krivci, ali samo oni, kažnjeni srazmerno svojoj krivici.25 Ali, takav nezavisan kriteri- 20 Ibidem. 21 Ibidem, str. 48. 22 Ibidem. 23 M. Volzer, Područje pravde, Beograd, 2000, str. 16 i dalje. 24 O. Hefe, Opus citatum, str. 48. 25 Ibidem. Dragan Mitrović [8] NBP • Žurnal za kriminalistiku i pravo jum ne postoji. A ne postoji ni pravni sistem koji nepogrešivo kažnjava samo krivce. Tim primerom Hefe samog sebe osporava: prvo, zato što brka materi- jalna sa proceduralnim pravilima, i drugo, zato što brka pravedan ishod (da su samo krivci kažnjeni) sa ispravno izvedenom procedurom (koja dozvoljava da se postigne takav pravedan cilj u obliku sudske pravičnosti). To i sam uviđa, kada priznaje da je „očigledno da ne postoji nikakav postupak koji isključuje sudske zablude i koji sprečava kažnjavanje nevinih kao i nekažnjavanje kriva- ca... suviše preoštro ili suviše blago“. Jasno je da takva relativna pravda nije ni pravna ni proceduralna. Treba skrenuti pažnju i na činjenicu da Hefe ne pravi jasnu razliku između proceduralne pravde26 (koja ne postoji) i prava na pravično suđenje27 (koje po- stoji). On, istina, navodi izreke „Da se čuje i druga strana“ (Audiatur et altea pars) i „Niko nije sudija u sopstvenoj stvari“ (Nemo ex iudex in causa sui), ali zanemaruje činjenicu da je pravo na pravično suđenje zbirni naziv za niz materijalnih pravila i preporuka o sprovođenju istražne i sudske procedure, a ne skup formalnih proceduralnih pravila koja ulaze u sastav proceduralne pravde. Takođe, on zanemaruje da se pravo na pravično suđenje odnosi na zaštitu prava ljudi u svim fazama postupka pred sudskim ili drugim držav- nim organima, kao i da se radi o materijalnim a ne proceduralnim pravilima. To potvrđuju najvažniji međunarodni dokumenti u kojima jasno stoji da ovo pravo predstavlja osnovno ljudsko pravo i da je jedno od opštevažećih nače- la. Kao takvo, ono ne može da bude samo proceduralne prirode. Na primer, pravo na pravično suđenje sadržano je u Univerzalnoj deklaraciji o ljudskim pravima, Međunarodnom paktu o građanskim i političkim pravima General- ne skupštine UN, Evropskoj konvenciji o ljudskim pravima i drugim sličnim međunarodnim ugovorima, pa čak i u normama međunarodnog običajnog prava. U svim dokumentima, a posebno u čl. 6 Evropske konvencije o ljud- skim pravima, određeni su međunarodni standardi vezani za pravo na pra- vično suđenje. Njihovo određivanje i razrada su zasnovani na ideji da kada se ljudska prava ne poštuju u policijskoj stanici, sobi za saslušavanje, pritvoru, sudu ili zatvorskoj ćeliji, da tada vlast očigledno ne ispunjava svoje obaveze. Očigledno, ta pravila su nadahnuta pravdom, možda i jesu pravedna, ali nisu proceduralna.28 26 Ibidem, str. 49. 27 Vid. N Mole, C. Harby, Pravo na pravično suđenje. Vodič za primenu člana 6 Evropske konvencije o ljudskim pravima, Beograd, 2003. 28 Međunarodni standardi za pravično suđenje mogu da se podele u dve grupe: na prava pre suđenja (pravo na slobodu, pravo pritvorenika na informaciju i kontakt sa spoljnim svetom, pravo na advokata pre suđenja, pravo na izvođenje pred sudiju ili drugi sudski organ u najkraćem mogućem roku, pravo na osporavanje zakonitosti pritvora, pravo na suđenje u razumnom roku ili na puštanje iz pritvora, pravo na adekvatno vreme i moguć- nosti za pripremu odbrane, prava tokom saslušanja, pravo na humanitarne uslove pritvora i zabrana torture) i prava na suđenju (pravo na jednakost pred zakonom i sudovima, pravo NBP • Journal of Criminalistics and Law [9] PROCEDURALNA PRAVDA, ISTINITOST I ISPRAVNOST Na kraju, Hefe zaključuje da se „mora voditi računa o poštenom postupa- nju prema učesnicima“, da se mora imati u vidu stvarna i lična nezavisnost sudija, javnost postupka, pravni lekovi, procesni rokovi itd., jer „bez pravne sigurnosti, kojoj oni služe, nema ni stvarne pravde“. Ali, ni tada se ne radi o proceduralnoj pravdi, već o pravilima koja treba da obezbede pravično suđe- nje. Njihov prvenstveni cilj nije pravednost već pravna sigurnost. 2. Istinitost i ispravnost Kao što je nagovešteno, cilj ovog rada nije da podrži ideju o postojanju proceduralne pravde, za šta se zalažu Džon Rols, Otfrid Hefe i drugi pisci, već da je ospori. To će biti pokazano pozivanjem na očigledno: da je pravda sino- nim za istinitost, a ne za nepristrasnost i ispravnost na kojima pisci pogrešno zasnivaju svoj pojam proceduralne pravde. Da pravdu treba izvoditi iz prirode, tj. istinitosti, potvrđuju brojni pisci koji pojam pravde izvode iz same prirode, od antičkih do savremenih. To važi i za Srbe, kod kojih je pravda uvek izvođena iz onog što „jeste“, što je prirodno i istinito. Pravda je „osnov svega“ (sv. Sava). Ona je istina jer „pravedno je samo ono što je istinito“ (D. Obradović). U protivnom, mora da je strašno verovati u neki autoritet kao istinu umesto u istinu kao jedini autoritet.29 Takvo tradicionalno metafizičko gledište ne dele svi pisci.30 Na primer, prema Peteru Koleru (Peter Koller) pravda je najvažniji deo morala, jer njeni standardi ne izražavaju samo ono što je dobro ili loše već i ono što je ispravno i pogrešno u našim odnosima sa drugim ljudima. To znači da Koler pojam pravde, koji se tradicionalno izvodi iz istinitosti, proširuje uvođenjem poj- ma ispravnosti.31 Drugi pisci, naročito u oblasti društvenih nauka, prihvataju na suđenje pred kompetentnim, nezavisnim, nepristrasnim i zakonom ustanovljenim su- dom, pravo na pravičnu raspravu, pravo na javnu raspravu, pretpostavka nevinosti, pravo da osoba ne bude prinuđena da svedoči protiv sebe ili da prizna krivicu, zabrana upotrebe dokaza iznuđenih torturom ili prinudom, zabrana retroaktivne primene krivičnih zakona i dvostruke ugroženosti /ne bis in idem/, pravo na suđenje bez nepotrebnog odlaganja, pravo da se osoba brani sama ili uz pomoć advokata, pravo osobe da prisustvuje suđenju i žalbenom postupku, pravo da se pozivaju i ispituju svedoci, pravo na tumača i na prevod, pravo na žalbu). Navedeni standardi takođe podrazumevaju da presude moraju da budu izrečene javno, da svako kome je suđeno mora da dobije obrazloženje sudske odluke, da mogu da sude samo sudije koje su učestvovale u postupku, da izrečene kazne moraju da budu individualne (a ne kolektivne), srazmerne, saglasne navedenim međunarodnim standardima itd. Vid. N. Mole; C. Harby, Opus citatum, str. 34−65. Nav. prema D. Mitro- vić, Teorija države i prava, Beograd, 2010, str. 534. 29 D. Mitrović, Opus citatum, str. 530. 30 Vid. M. Trajković, Etička dimenzija prava – pravnoteorijski aspekt, Novi Sad, 2008. 31 P. Koler, O socijalnoj pravdi, Anali Pravnog fakulteta u Beogradu, br. 1/2005, str. 8, 11. Dragan Mitrović [10] NBP • Žurnal za kriminalistiku i pravo „zdravo za gotovo“ da proceduralna pravda postoji i taj konstrukt umnožavaju izmišljajući različite simulakrume, tj. različite vrste proceduralne pravde koje takođe ne postoje (npr., krivične proceduralne pravde, a zašto ne i građanske proceduralne pravde, upravne proceduralne pravde itd.). Možda je zbog toga pravi trenutak da se iznese nekoliko zapažanja o od- nosu istinitosti i ispravnosti uopšte (koji postoji), a zatim i o odnosu pravde i proceduralne pravde (koji ne postoji). Pre svega, proceduralna pravna pravila mogu da obezbede samo ispravnost u smislu pravilnosti, predvidljivosti i pouzdanosti (npr., u skladu sa prime- nom materijalnih pravila nepristrasnosti i poštenja, fer-pleja), ali ne mogu da obezbede istinitost i pravednost. Ispravnost je pravilno postupanje. Nešto je ispravno urađeno zato što je izvedeno na pravilan, sistematski i stručan na- čin, a ne zato što je istinito ili pravedno. Tu se istinitost pojavljuje samo kao mogući cilj ili poželjan rezultat, a ne kao sastojak odnosne procedure koja je samo sredstvo za moguće postizanje tog željenog cilja. Ispravnost je naročito važna za pravo, koje je ispravno kada je pogodno za rad, odnosno neisprav- no kada nije pogodno za rad.32 Dakle, proceduralna pravda ne može da bude ništa više osim „primenjivačke ispravnosti“. Takva ispravnost je korisna jer može da posluži kao „pouzdano merilo“ i „rukovodno načelo“.33 Ali, to nema nikakve veze sa pravdom koja ima svoju vlastitu svrhu („nadsvrhu“), naročito kada je nadahnutu milosrđem. Isti odnos je moguće razmatrati na drugačiji i moderniji način, iz ugla pri- rodnih nauka, koje istinitosti više ne određuju kao apsolutan već kao relati- van pojam. Danas mnogi filozofi prirode i teoretičari verovatnoće smatraju da umesto izraza „istina“ i ,„pravda“ treba koristiti izraze „verovatnoća“ i „kon- kretnost“.34 Po njima, može se govoriti samo o „stepenima istinitosti“. Njima odgovaraju „različiti stepeni verovatnoće“ koja teži da na kraju postane pot- puna, apsolutna istina. To znači da raspravljanje o istini u tradicionalnom i apsolutnom smislu treba zameniti raspravljanjem u modernom i relativnom smislu o „stepenima istinitosti“, „stepenima racionalne vere“ ili „stepenima verovatnosti“ (Dž. M. Kejns / J. M. Keynes).35 Saglasno sa tim, istina se ne smatra samo relativnom već i nedostižnom vrednošću, osim u jednom sluča- ju, kada je zbilja dostižna. To je slučaj kada se istina ostvari (utvrdi i potvrdi). Dotle se može govoriti samo o „stepenima istinitosti“ (H. Rajhenbah / H. Re- ichenbach, H. Džefriz / H. Jeffris, K. Poper / K. Popper)36 izražene u obliku 32 H. Jeffreys, Theory of Probability, Oxford Un. Press, 1948, str. 17−18. 33 A. Ros, Pravo i pravda, Beograd – Podgorica, 1996, str. 57 i dalje. 34 Filozofijski riječnik, Zagreb, 1965, str. 190−194, 381, 431. 35 Vid. J. M. Keynes, A Treatise of Probability, London, 1957, str. 71−78. 36 H. Reichenbach, The Rise of Scientific Philosophy, Un. of California Press, Barkley, 1968, str. 411; H. Jeffris, Theory of Probability, Oxford 1948, str. 341; K. Poper, Traganje bez kraja. Intelektualna autobiografija, Beograd, 1991, str. 93. NBP • Journal of Criminalistics and Law [11] PROCEDURALNA PRAVDA, ISTINITOST I ISPRAVNOST „skalirane izvesnosti“ da je nešto istinito. Na suprotnom kraju iste skale nalazi se „pogrešnost“. Dakle, kada tvrdimo da je nešto istinito, smatraju navedeni pisci, tada kažemo samo to da lično pretpostavljamo da je nešto istinito. I ni- kada ne možemo da ustvrdimo da to nešto zbilja jeste potpuno istinito, osim u pomenutom izuzetku. To je razlog zašto pisci predlažu „pogodnost za rad“ kao osnovno istraživačevo rukovodno načelo, a ne istinitost dobijenih iskaza koji u krajnjem pripadaju našem referencijalnom sistemu (L. Vitgenštajn / L. Vittgenstein).37 Na ukratko izložena shvatanja o istini i pravdi u prirodnim naukama nado- vezuje se novi deskriptivni pristupi naučnika iz različitih društvenih oblasti. I oni se više usredsređuju na individualno shvatanje istine i pravde, dakle, na ono što pojedinci smatraju pravednim, a manje na definitivna ili istinita ap- straktna metateorijska određenja pravde. Na primer, neki pisci svoja istraživa- nja usmeravaju na istraživanje pravednosti i ispravnosti u oblastima društve- ne razmene, ugovaranja, kupovine itd., tj. u poslovnim odnosima uopšte (Dž. Grinberg / J. Greenberg) dok se drugi bave pravdom sa stanovišta posedovanja bogatstva i društvene moći (R. Nozik / R. Nozick), mogućnosti za obrazova- nje, dostupnosti medicinske zaštite (F. d’Agostino / F. d’Agostino). Takođe, pre- ispituju se priroda organizacione pravde, procedure pravednog prosuđivanja u organizacijama (R. Korpanzano / R. Corpanzano, B. Ambroz / B. Abrose) ili oblici kontrole u organizaciji (R. Šapiro / R. Shapio, E. Bret / E. Brett). Istražuju se i efekti pravde prema posledicama ispravnog ili neispravnog tretmana na radnom mestu (M. Van den Bos, G. Konlon / G. Konlon). Najzad, oživljavaju se pitanja određivanja pravde u međunarodnim odnosima (R. Dž. Bajes / R. J. Bies).38 Izgleda da su navedena istraživanja u prirodnim i društvenim na- ukama dala zamah autorima u pravnim naukama da se sve češće i upornije zalažu za postojanje proceduralne pravde (npr., u slučaju „normi i postupaka alokacije dobara“).39 Kako god bilo, ono što važi za istinu, treba da važi i za pravdu. Ipak, tvrd- nja o pravdi kao nedostižnoj vrednosti, kao i tvrdnja o istini kao nedostižnoj vrednosti, nije prihvatljiva, jer se istina ipak saznaje a pravda uliva u pozi- tivno pravo, tj. povremeno se ovaploćuje u njemu u obliku pravičnosti. To dozvoljava da se zaključi kako pravda ipak postoji (kao i istina, i to ne samo u perfektu, kao nešto što je dostignuto ili ostvareno), dakle, ne samo onako kako predlažu savremeni pisci. Takođe, ne može se smatrati tačnom ni tvrdnja da je pravda relativna u smislu skaliranja. Tu je pre reč o stepenu ostvarivanja nastojanja (uspešnosti) da se dostigne pravda. Uz to, pitanje je da li relativna pravda uopšte može da bude pravedna. Ako ništa drugo, sigurno je da postoji 37 Vid. L. Vitgenštajn, O izvesnosti, Novi Sad, 1988 38 Vid. B. Ratković Njegovan, Pravda i poslovanje, Škola biznisa, Novi Sad, 2015, str. 169−176. 39 Ibidem, str. 174. Dragan Mitrović [12] NBP • Žurnal za kriminalistiku i pravo nepromenljiva zamisao pravde koja čoveka motiviše da je dostigne, u čemu on povremeno i uspeva, uprkos tome što je tako „srećno udešen da nema nika- kvog tačnog merila istinitosti“, ali zato ima „više izvrsnih merila netačnosti“.40 Čovek nije samo racionalno već i intuitivno biće. Time se može objasniti zašto ima toliko pogrešnih predstava o istini, pravdi i njenim vrstama. Možda je od razmatranja odnosa istinitosti i ispravnosti važnije istaći da se istinitost i ispravnost ne podudaraju, kako god da se određuju u apsolut- nom ili relativnom smislu. Nešto što je istinito ne mora da bude ispravno sa proceduralnog stanovišta (npr., kada sud utvrdi materijalnu istinu, ali zbog neispravno izvedenih pravila procedure mora krivca da oslobodi krivice). I obrnuto, nešto što je ispravno ne mora da bude istinito (npr., kada se pravi- la procedure ispravno izvode ali rezultat nije istinit zbog pogrešno utvrđene materijalne istine). Očigledno, reč je odnosu cilja (istinitosti, pravde ili pravič- nosti) i sredstva (ispravnosti, pravilnosti, predvidljivosti, korektnosti, tj. so- lidnosti izvedenog postupka). Ta veza pokazuje da je ispravnost prvenstveno sredstvo za nepristrasnu primenu prava, a tek zatim i u drugom redu sredstvo za moguće postizanje pravičnosti u pravu. Takođe, navedeni odnos pokazuje da samo materijalna pravna pravila mogu da budu pravedna, dok to ne može da bude slučaj sa proceduralnim pravilima (npr., pravilo da se proceduralna pravila nepristrasno i pošteno primenjuju pripada materijalnom pravu i samo se to pravilo u ovom primeru može smatrati pravednim, dok se sama proce- duralna pravila ne mogu smatrati takvim jer je za njih dovoljno samo da budu ispravno izvedena, i to u skladu sa pomenutim materijalnim pravilom). Razmatranje odnosa istinitosti i ispravnosti na primeru stvarno postojeće pravde i stvarno nepostojeće proceduralne pravde pokreće još jedno važno pi- tanje, a to je pitanje odnosa materijalnog (supstancijalnog) i formalnog (pro- ceduralnog) prava. Prvo se odnosi na opšte pravne norme koje se razvrstaju prema svojoj sadržini, a drugo na opšte pravne norme koje se razvrstaju prema svom obliku.41 Ali i ova je podela „u velikoj meri veštačka, kao i prethodne 40 B. Paskal, Misli, Beograd, 1988, str. 72, t. 82. 41 Da podsetimo, u materijalno pravo spadaju „sve norme bilo koje pravne grane koje za odnosne pravne subjekte utvrđuju ovlašćenja, obaveze i predviđaju sankciju za njihovu povredu (norme o pravima i dužnostima supružnika, roditelja i dece, pravima građana, pravima i obavezama parlamenta, šefa države, vlade, sudova, pravima i obavezama ugo- vornih strana, naknadi štete itd.)“. Te norme su primarne jer sačinjavaju suštinu prava. U formalno pravo spadaju pravne norme koje regulišu „spoljašnji oblik i postupke za ostva- rivanje prava, tj. norme krivičnog i građanskog sudskog postupka ili upravnog, arbitraž- nog ili nekog drugog sličnog postupka (norme o načinu sklapanja i raskidanja ugovora, o načinu sklapanja i razvoda braka, o formularima koji se ispunjavaju prilikom prijave poreza, o upisu birača u biračke spiskove itd.) Norme formalnog prava su sekundarne jer je njihov glavni zadatak da služe ostvarivanju primarnih materijalnih normi... Treba po- menuti i da većina pravnih normi ima materijalni karakter, a tek njihov manji deo proce- duralni (instrumentalni) karakter, sve to kako bi se omogućilo bolje donošenje i uspešnija primena materijalnih pravnih normi“. Nav. prema D. Mitrović, Opus citatum, str. 219. NBP • Journal of Criminalistics and Law [13] PROCEDURALNA PRAVDA, ISTINITOST I ISPRAVNOST podele, jer nije uvek lako utvrditi da li izvesna norma spada u materijalno ili formalno pravo“.42 Da je zbilja reč o veštačkoj i nepouzdanoj podeli pokazuju prikazana učenja Rolsa i Hefea, ali i Kolera, u kojima se pravila materijalnog prava, koja se odnose na primenu čisto proceduralnih pravila, svrstavaju u proceduralna pravila. Drugim rečima, zato što nije moguće jasno i do kra- ja razgraničiti jedna od drugih, zagovornici proceduralne pravde materijalna pravila koja se odnose na procedure proglašavaju proceduralnim, sve to kako bi se konstruisao pojam proceduralne pravde. Ni to se ne može prihvatiti jer, npr., pravilo nepristrasnosti i pravilo poštenja nalažu samo da se proceduralna pravila ispravno primenjuju. Ovim pravilima, kao i drugim, određuje se način sprovođenja čisto proceduralnih pravila. Nije isto odnositi se na nešto i biti nešto. Zbog toga pravilo nepristrasnosti i pravilo poštenja pripadaju materi- jalnom pravu. Kako god bilo, odnos materijalnog i formalnog prava pokazuje da je isprav- nost, a time i tzv. proceduralna pravda, samo sredstvo za primenu prava. Tako- đe, on pokazuje da samo materijalna pravna pravila mogu da budu pravedna, dok to ne može da bude slučaj sa proceduralnim pravilima. To dozvoljava da se zaključi još nešto: da je istinitost sinonim za pravdu, a ispravnost sinonim za postupke koji sami po sebi nisu niti moraju da budu ispravni, a još manje istiniti u smislu pravednosti. Dakle, ispravnost ne može da bude sinonim za pravdu i tzv. proceduralnu pravdu. U još dubljoj senci nalazi se pitanje odnosa prirodnog i pozitivnog prava.43 Izgleda da se istrajavanje na postojanju proceduralne pravde može smatrati zakasnelim odgovorom pripadnika pozitivističke jurisprudencije. Neobično je da se za postojanje proceduralne pravde zalažu i pisci koji izvorno pripadaju pravcu prirodnopravne jurisprudencije. Naročito zagovornici pozitivističkih pravnih shvatanja istrajavaju na razlikovanju pozitivnog od prirodnog prava i pravde kao istinitosti od ispravnosti kao pravilnosti. Takav pristup mogao bi se nazvati naučnim, a ne filozofskim. On nalaže pravnicima realistima-po- zitivistima da prema pravu zauzmu objektivan, vrednosno i etički neutralan stav, budući da norma, naročito proceduralna, ne mora da bude vezana ni za kakav sistem društvenih i pravnih vrednosti (npr., postizanje opšteg dobra, ostvarenje pravde, zaštita ljudskih sloboda itd.). Da su odstupili od takve vred- nosne i etičke neutralnosti pokazuje to što isti ti pravnici pozitivisti sve češće merilom pravednosti smatraju činjenicu da je norma ispravno primenjena, tačno prema određenoj proceduri, kao i da je samo to dovoljno da se pozitiv- no pravo smatra pravednim. Takva tvrdnja ne može da se prihvati ima li se u vidu da pozitivisti pravo izvode „odozdo na gore“ (kakav je u novije vreme sve 42 Ibidem, 220. 43 Vid. M. Trajković, Vrednosna usmerenost prava naspram pravnog pozitivizma, Anali Pravnog fakulteta u Beogradu, god. 62, br. 1/2014, str. 102−113. Dragan Mitrović [14] NBP • Žurnal za kriminalistiku i pravo češće slučaj sa pripadnicima anglosaksonskog pravca jurisprudencije) kao i da ga zasnivaju samo na svetu fizičke stvarnosti, umesto i na svetu metafizičke stvarnosti, jer je pravo u isto vreme realna i idealna pojava.44 Oni pogrešno svet fizičke stvarnosti poistovećuju sa svetom pravne stvarnosti (koja je vrsta „nadstvarnosti“, metastvarnosti), dok čisto idejni pravni svet (svet meta-me- tapravne stvarnosti) isključuju iz svojih razmatranja. Uprkos tim odlučujućim nedostacima, oni i dalje, zbog navodne pravednosti proceduralnih pravila, i samo pozitivno pravo rado smatraju pravednim.45 A upravo taj pravni meta- svet i meta-metapravni svet (ili „svet 2“ i „svet 3“, kako ih naziva K. Poper), koji pravnici pozitivisti osporavaju i odbacuju, pokazuje da unutar prava kao metasveta postoje dva posebna sveta, tj. dva njegova posebna obrasca: prav- ni svet pravila (metasvet materijalnih pravila) i pravni svet meta-metapravila (svet proceduralnih pravila). Prvim se uređuje sadržaj pravnog saobraćanja, a drugim utvrđuje poredak ispravnog odvijanja pravnih pravila i ljudskog ponašanja po njima.46 Kada bi samo ispravno sprovođenje procedure moglo pozitivnom pravu da pribavi svojstvo pravednosti, veoma brzo bi došlo do pravne anarhije. Šta više, svaki poredak bi mogao da se nazove pravednim zbog ispravne primene prava. To znači da bi legitimnim mogao da se smatra i pravni poredak u kome se pravo uvek ne primenjuje ispravno. Očigledno, ispravnost je nužan uslov za primenu i normalno ostvarivanje prava, ali nije osnov njegove pravednosti. 3. Pravičnost kao mesto susretanja istinitosti i ispravnosti Između pravde i procedure se nalazi pravičnost kao mesto susretanja i po- dudaranja pravde kao istinitosti i ispravnosti kao pravilnosti (pouzdanosti i korektnosti, tj. solidnosti). To posredno priznaju i pisci koji se zalažu za proce- duralnu pravdu, naročito oni koji pokušavaju da pronađu nekakav oslonac za proceduralnu pravdu u pravilima materijalnog prava. Zbog toga svesno brkaju materijalne sa proceduralnim normama. Ali, proceduralna pravda ne postoji dok pravda postoji, samo ona nije proceduralna, kao ni pravičnost, koja se može smatrati operativnim i primenjivačkim oblikom pravde.47 44 Vid. D. Mitrović, Idealistički i realistički pojam prava, Anali Pravnog fakulteta u Beo- gradu, god. LXI, br. 1/2013, str. 29−52. 45 Vid. M. Trajković, Pravo u svetu vrednosti, Zbornik radova Pravni fakulteta u Novom Sadu, god. 46, br. 1/2012, str. 383−398. 46 D. Mitrović, Put prava. Holistička paradigma sveta i prava u svetlu teorije haosa i pravne teorije, Beograd, 2000, str. 221, 228−229. 47 Da podsetimo, pravičnost (aequitas, iustus) jeste pravda u konkretnom slučaju koji ne može da se reši samo na osnovu pozitivnog prava. Prvo je smatrana vrlinom zakonske NBP • Journal of Criminalistics and Law [15] PROCEDURALNA PRAVDA, ISTINITOST I ISPRAVNOST Da je pravičnost mesto susretanja i ukrštanja istinitosti i ispravnosti, po- kazuje veza prirodnog i pozitivnog prava koja omogućava da se pravila pri- rodnog prava prelivaju u pravila pozitivnog prava. Ta veza dozvoljava da se pravičnost odredi u prirodnopravnom i pozitivnopravnom smislu. Pravičnost „u prirodnopravnom smislu postoji kada zakon neposredno upućuje na pri- rodno pravo u slučajevima pravnih praznina (kada ne postoje pravne odredbe za pojedine slučajeve koje zakon nije predvideo ili sudija nije mogao da ih podvede pod neku opštu normu). S druge strane, pravičnost u pozitivnoprav- nom smislu raspolaže svojim zakonskim (materijalnim) i sudskim (formal- nim) oblikom. Zakonska pravičnost u pozitivnopravnom smislu omogućava da se pravna norma primeni tako što će biti uzete u obzir sve osobenosti nekog slučaja. Takve norme spadaju u pravično pravo (koje nalaže odustajanje od kažnjavanja za sitnu krađu, utaju, prevaru iz nevolje itd.), za razliku od strogog prava koje ne dopušta uzimanje u obzir takvih osobenosti. Sudska pravičnost u pozitivnopravnom smislu postoji kada se rešavanje zakonom obuhvaćenih konkretnih slučajeva vrši u duhu prava, tj. njegove ideje, materije, a ne pre- ma slovu zakona. Do toga obično dolazi kada zakonom nisu obuhvaćena sva obeležja konkretnog slučaja (slučaj pravne praznine). Tada sudska pravičnost omogućava sudiji da reši konkretan slučaj prema pravilu koje sam određu- je“.48 Proizilazi da pravo samo preko pravičnosti može da služi ostvarenju ideje pravde (Aristotel), a ne preko proceduralne pravde (Rols, Hefe i drugi). Slična misao susreće se u Radbruhovoj Filozofiji prava: pravo je stvarnost koja svoje značenje ima u činjenici da služi ideji pravde. Sporno je i mesto proceduralne pravde pored zakonske i sudske pravde. Kada bi zbilja postojala proceduralna pravda, zakonska i sudska pravda po- stale bi njene vrste. Ali, time obuhvat proceduralne pravde ne bi bio iscrpljen, jer bi ona trebalo da se odnosi i na sva proceduralna pravila koja donose drugi društveni subjekti. To pokazuje da je proceduralna pravda i u tom smislu ne- jasno zamišljena i određena, što nije slučaj sa proceduralnim pravilima koja moraju da budu što određenija i jasnija zbog njihove ispravne primene. pravde, da bi u XIX i XX veku postala sredstvo za ispravljanje preterane strogosti zakona, naročito kada treba da se spreči mehanička, nezakonita ili nepravedna primena pravila u konkretnim slučajevima. Tako se postupa i danas, kada se pravičnošću naziva ustavno ili običajno ovlašćenje sudija ili drugih službenih lica da elastično primenjuju pravne norme u konkretnim slučajevima radi uspešnijeg ostvarivanja prava. Zbog toga se pravičnost do- življava kao korektivna pravda, jedna vrsta poštenja koje ispravlja pravo a ukrašava prav- du. Viši oblik tog ukrašavanja predstavlja milosrđe, koje predsedava nad samom pravdom. 48 Nav. prema D. Mitrović, Teorija države i prava, str. 532−534. Dragan Mitrović [16] NBP • Žurnal za kriminalistiku i pravo Zaključak Tvrditi da postoji proceduralna pravda znači prikloniti se onom što je po- modno u pravnoj nauci. Pravnici pozitivisti u tome mogu da pronađu zado- voljenje, jer, eto, i pozitivno pravo je pravedno, makar samo u proceduralnom smislu. S druge strane, pravnici prirodnopravne orijentacije, preterujući sa proširivanjem pojma pravde, takođe čine rđavu uslugu sebi i pravnicima po- zitivistima. Počeli su da zagovaraju postojanje proceduralne pravde, da barem preko nje pozitivno pravo postane pravedno. Zanemarili su da proceduralna pravda ne postoji dok pravda postoji, kao i da pravda nije proceduralna, što nije ni pravičnost. Da proceduralna ne postoji, može se pokazati sledećim tvrdnjama: − pravda je sinonim za istinitost, a ne za ispravnost na kojoj pomenuti pisci grade pojam proceduralne pravde; − istinitost se odnosi na ono što jeste, što postoji, a ispravnost na pravilno i precizno izvođenje odgovarajućih postupaka; − istinitost i ispravnost se ne podudaraju, isto kao što se ne podudaraju pravda i pravo; nešto što je istinito ne mora da bude ispravno; i obrnuto, nešto što je ispravno ne mora da bude istinito; − veza istinitosti i ispravnosti pokazuje da je reč je odnosu cilja (istinitosti, pravde i pravičnosti) i sredstva (ispravnosti, korektnosti, preciznosti, pouzda- nosti itd., rečju solidnosti); − proceduralna pravda se često pogrešno izvodi iz materijalnih pravila o procedurama koja se zatim proglašavaju proceduralnim (npr., princip nepri- strasnosti ili princip poštenja nalažu da se proceduralna pravila ispravno i fer primenjuju: ona pripadaju materijalnom a ne proceduralnom pravu zbog toga što se njima određuje način sprovođenja čisto proceduralnih pravila); nije isto odnositi se na nešto i biti nešto; − istinitosti i ispravnost, tj. pravda i procedura, povremeno se podudaraju i tada se ispoljavaju u obliku pravičnosti. Kada bi se prihvatila tvrdnja da proceduralna pravda postoji, tada bi se i Hitlerovi rasistički Nirnberški zakoni mogli smatrati pravednim samo zato što su doneti na pravno ispravan način. Ili, u blažem slučaju, svako ispravno i po- šteno sprovođenje pravila procedure uopšte moglo bi da se smatra pravednim, dok bi neispravna primena istih proceduralnih pravila bila pravno prihvat- ljiva, samo se ona ne bi mogla nazvati pravednom u proceduralnom smislu. Očigledno, reč je o opasnom simulakrumu koji materiju prava zamenjuje nje- govom formom (procedurom), istinu ispravnošću, a pravdu proizvoljnošću. Istrajavanje na postojanju proceduralne pravde može se smatrati i zakasne- lim odgovorom pripadnika pozitivističke jurisprudencije, kao što je rečeno. Neobično je da se za postojanje proceduralne pravde zalažu i pisci koji izvorno NBP • Journal of Criminalistics and Law [17] PROCEDURALNA PRAVDA, ISTINITOST I ISPRAVNOST pripadaju pravcu prirodnopravne jurisprudencije. Valjda i jedni i drugi imaju isti cilj, samo iz različitih razloga: da pozitivno pravo predstave kao praved- no. Ali, to više nije Rolsov i Hefeov konstrukt već simulakrum proceduralne pravde, koji rado prisvajaju pravnici pozitivisti, a podržavaju prirodnopravno orijentisani pravnici. I da zaključimo: proceduralna pravda ne postoji, ali se do pravde može doći ispravnim postupcima. I obrnuto, pravda postoji, ali ona nije proceduralna, što nije ni pravičnost. Procedura je jedino ispravno sredstvo prava, ali pravo nije jedino ispravno sredstvo pravde. Literatura 1. Aristotel; Nikomahova etika, Beograd, 1970. 2. Di Džordž, R. T; Poslovna etika, Beograd, 2003. 3. Dvorkin, R; Carstvo prava, Beograd, 2003. 4. Dworkin, R; Shvaćanje prava ozbiljno, Zagreb, 2003. 5. Filozofijski riječnik, Zagreb, 1965. 6. Glintić, T; Pogovor knjizi Dž. Rolsa Teorija pravde, Beograd – Podgorica, 1998. 7. Hefe, O; Pravda. Filozofski uvod, Novi Sad, 1998. 8. Holbah, P; Sistem prirode, Beograd, 1950. 9. Jeffris, H; Theory of Probability, Oxford 1948. 10. Jovanov, I; Pravda. Filozofski uvod, Zbornik Pravnog fakulteta u Novom Sadu, br. 2/2014. 11. Kant, I; Zasnivanje metafizike morala, Beograd, 2008. 12. Kelzen, H; Elementi teorije pravnih normi. Pozni izabrani spisi, Beograd – Podgorica, 2003. 13. Keynes, J. M; A Treatise of Probability, London, 1957. 14. Koler, P; O socijalnoj pravdi, Anali Pravnog fakulteta u Beogradu, br. 1/2005. 15. Mitrović, D; Teorija države i prava, Beograd, 2010. 16. Mitrović, D; Idealistički i realistički pojam prava, Anali Pravnom fakultetu u Beogradu, god. LXI, br. 1/2013. 17. Mitrović, D; Put prava. Holistička paradigma sveta i prava u svetlu teorije haosa i pravne teorije, Beograd, 2000. Dragan Mitrović [18] NBP • Žurnal za kriminalistiku i pravo 18. Mole, N; Harby C; Pravo na pravično suđenje. Vodič za primenu člana 6 Evropske konvencije o ljudskim pravima, Beograd, 2003. 19. Nozik, R; Anarhija, država, utopija, Zagreb, 2003. 20. Paskal, B; Misli, Beograd, 1988. 21. Poper, K; Traganje bez kraja. Intelektualna autobiografija, Beograd, 1991. 22. Radbruh, G; Filozofija prava, Beograd, 1980 (2016). 23. Ratković Njegovan, B; Pravda i poslovanje, Škola biznisa, Novi Sad, 2015. 24. Reichenbach, H; The Rise of Scientific Philosophy, Un. of California Press, Barkley, 1968. 25. Rols, Dž; Teorija pravde, Beograd – Podgorica, 1998. 26. Ros, A; Pravo i pravda, Beograd – Podgorica, 1996. 27. Ruso, Ž. Ž; Rasprava o porijeklu i osnovama nejednakosti među ljudima, Zagreb, 1978. 28. Sovilj, B. B; Put kroz pravo do pravde, Petrovaradin, 2004. 29. Trajković, M; Vrednosna usmerenost prava naspram pravnog pozitivizma, Anali Pravnog fakulteta u Beogradu, god. 62, br. 1/2014. 30. Trajković, M; Pravo u svetu vrednosti, Zbornik radova Pravni fakulteta u Novom Sadu, god. 46, br. 1/2012. 31. Trajković, M; Etička dimenzija prava – pravnoteorijski aspekt, Novi Sad, 2008. 32. Vitgenštajn, L; O izvesnosti, Novi Sad, 1988. 33. Volzer, M; Područje pravde, Beograd, 2000. 34. Vučković, Ž; Biznis i moral, 2006. 35. Živanović, T; Sistem sintetičke filozofije prava, III, Beograd, 1959. NBP • Journal of Criminalistics and Law [19] PROCEDURALNA PRAVDA, ISTINITOST I ISPRAVNOST PROCEDURAL JUSTICE, TRUTHFULNESS AND RIGHTNESS Dragan M. Mitrović University of Belgrade, Faculty of Law It must be difficult to believe in any authority as truth instead in truth as the only authority. Abstract: The aim of this work is not to support the idea of the ex- istence of procedural justice, advocated by the best known propo- nents of the existence of procedural justice (J. Rawls and O. Höffe, and then by L. Fuller, H. Hart, R. Dworkin, P. Koller, M. Van den Bos and others), but to consider procedural justice from the angle of truthfulness and rightness. Since it is not about the same but related concepts, it is rendered possible to conclude that truth- fulness and rightness are incongruent, in the same way as justice and the law are incongruent. Something that is truthful does not need to be righteous. And vice versa, something that is righteous does not need to be truthful. Obviously, it has to do with the rela- tionship between the goal (truthfulness, justice and fairness) and means (properness, correctness, preciseness, reliability, etc. in a word, solidity). The consideration of the relationship of truthfulness and right- ness in the example of the actually existing justice and the actual- ly non-existent procedural justice, gives rise to further important questions: the relationship of material (substantive) and formal (procedural) legal rules, fairness as the meeting place of justice, the law and procedure, etc. In a yet deeper shadow lies the ques- tion of the relationship between natural law and positive law. It can be concluded that procedural justice does not exist. But, justice exists, only it is not procedural, which neither is fairness. Procedure is the only righteous means of the law, but the law is not the only righteous means of justice. Keywords: justice, fairness, truthfulness, rightness, procedural law, procedural justice. work_4je7pa3aqrbwrgwuatif7nrni4 ---- Restorative Justice and Procedural Justice: Dealing with Rule Breaking Journal of Social Issues, Vol. 62, No. 2, 2006, pp. 307--326 Restorative Justice and Procedural Justice: Dealing with Rule Breaking Tom R. Tyler∗ New York University This article identifies similarities among three approaches to dealing with rule breaking: the procedural justice model, the restorative justice model, and the study of moral development. Each argues that the long-term goal when dealing with rule breaking is to motivate rule breakers to become more self-regulating in their future conduct. This goal is undermined by punishment-focused models of sanctioning. Sanction-based models, which dominate current thinking about managing criminals, have negative consequences for the individual wrongdoer and for society. It is argued that greater focus needs to be placed on psychological approaches whose goal is to connect with and activate internal values within wrongdoers with the goal of encouraging self-regulatory law-related behavior in the future. In the last several decades, America could perhaps best be characterized as a highly “punitive” society (Roberts & Stalans, 2000; Tyler, Boeckmann, Smith, & Huo, 1997; Whitman, 2003). The focus of public attention has been on the need to punish rule-breakers and support has been high for harsh punishments for a wide variety of crimes, punishments including the death penalty and life in prison. The general tenor of recent times is captured by the case of support for the death penalty. During the 1960s, a majority of adult Americans favored ending the death penalty, while public opinion polls during the 1980s–1990s typically found that 80% or more of those interviewed favored the death penalty (Ellsworth & Gross, 1994). The focus of public discussion has been, in this and many other ways, on the view that the legal system is too lenient and that there need to be harsher ways to punish those who commit crimes. These punitive aspects of American culture are striking because they have become stronger during recent decades. A person looking at American society in ∗Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to Tom R. Tyler, Department of Psychology, New York University, 6 Washington Place, Room 579, New York, NY 10003 [e-mail: tom.tyler@nyu.edu]. 307 C© 2006 The Society for the Psychological Study of Social Issues 308 Tyler the 1960s might have projected a future of declining punishment and increasing efforts at rehabilitation and reintegration for offenders (Garland, 2001). For exam- ple, during the 1960s the majority of adult Americans opposed the death penalty, the result of steady declines in support since the 1930s. That is, in fact, the di- rection taken by much of Europe (Whitman, 2003). However, the United States has not moved in that direction. Instead, it has become a more punitive society in which harsh punishment is central to reactions to rule breaking (Garland, 2001; Whitman, 2003). Central to this punitive society is a model in which the primary way of mo- tivating compliance with the law is via the application of sanctions. There have been several negative consequences of this sanction orientation. One is that it has led to a swelling of the prison population, with the result that America is now one of the leading countries in the world in terms of the proportion of its adult population held in jails and prisons (Haney & Zimbardo, 1998). This statistic itself does not capture the true impact of the large prison population. That impact has been disproportionately upon the poor and minorities whose communities have been decimated, as large numbers of young minority males have spent time in prisons. In addition, this punitive orientation toward the population has made more negative the relationship between the police, courts, and the residents of American communities (Tyler, 1997, 1998; Tyler & Huo, 2002). In an effort to lessen serious crime, for example, the New York city police have punished more severely minor crimes, such as drinking in public parks. Instead of receiving a minor penalty for such crimes, people have been brought into police stations, booked, and held in jail overnight. In recent years, this has led to punitive experiences, including being jailed overnight or for weekends, for a much larger proportion of the cities’ youth than in past years (Tyler & Huo, 2002), with resulting hostility toward the police. While not the only punitive policy enacted by police, this approach to social control typifies the use of force to secure compliance, and the public hostility that results. Many legal authorities acknowledge these negative consequences, but regard them as the inevitable byproducts of engaging in effective social regulation (Nagin, 1998). Other Approaches Procedural justice research suggests that there is another possible route to effective social regulation besides punitive punishment (Tyler, 1990; Tyler & Huo, 2002). This route involves treating people with procedural justice and respect. When people are so treated, they view law and legal authorities as more legitimate and entitled to be obeyed. As a result, people become self-regulating, taking on the personal responsibility for following social rules. This approach has been labeled a process-based model of regulation (Tyler, 2003, 2006). Restorative Justice and Procedural Justice 309 These procedural justice findings can be put within a larger framework of social engagement, in which we seek to understand how to constructively engage people in society and social institutions. Research suggests that the key to doing so is to create groups, organizations, and societies within which people experi- ence procedural justice (Tyler, 1990; Tyler & Blader, 2000; Tyler & Huo, 2002). Two types of procedural justice are key: justice in the quality of decision-making procedures and justice in the quality of treatment that people receive from others. When people experience these forms of justice, they are found to accept social rules, and voluntarily engage in self-regulatory behavior (Tyler & Blader, 2000; Tyler & Huo, 2002). The importance of procedural justice research is that its findings point to the potential viability of models of regulation that rely upon self-regulatory motiva- tions. Research suggests that people will obey laws, without the threat of sanctions, when they experience the criminal justice system and its authorities as acting justly. Hence, there are viable models of proactive social regulation that do not generate the negative consequences associated with punitive, sanctioning, approaches to rule breaking. The goal of this review is to point to common elements shared by this proce- dural justice approach, the restorative justice movement, and a focus on morality and moral development. These approaches are united by their common goal: to encourage the development or activation of people’s internal values so that they will become more motivated to engage in self-regulatory behavior. It is suggested that a civil society is most effective when its members buy into commonly held values and follow rules because they are motivated to do so, rather than because they are motivated by incentives or sanctions. Shaping People’s Behavior The roots of these approaches lie in an analysis of the nature of human motiva- tion. Kurt Lewin (Gold, 1999) distinguished between two core elements in human motivation. One source of motivation is the basic desire to maximize gain and min- imize loss in interactions with others. These are “instrumental” or “self-interested” motivations. The underlying assumption of Lewin’s model of motivation is that shaping the external environment by providing incentives or threatening sanctions is one way to shape people’s behaviors. This model of motivation is frequently referred to as the deterrence or social control model (Nagin, 1998), and it has dominated American thinking about how to control crime during the last several decades. Such models focus on the ability of legal authorities and institutions to shape people’s behavior by threatening to deliver or by actually delivering negative sanc- tions for rule breaking. To implement such deterrence strategies, police officers carry guns and clubs, and can threaten citizens with physical injury, incapacitation, 310 Tyler or financial penalties. Their goal is to establish their authority and “The uniform, badge, truncheon, and arms all may play a role in asserting authority” in the effort to “gain control of the situation (Reiss, 1971, p. 46).” The police seek to control the individual’s behavior “by manipulating an individual’s calculus regarding whether “crime pays” in the particular instance (Meares, 2000, p. 396).” Judges similarly shape people’s acceptance of their decisions by threatening fines or even jail time for failure to comply. Research suggests that the ability to threaten and/or deliver sanctions is often effective in shaping people’s law-related behavior (Nagin, 1998). In particular, a number of studies on deterrence suggest that people are less likely to engage in illegal behaviors when they think that they might be caught and punished for wrongdoing (Nagin & Paternoster, 1991; Paternoster, 1987, 1989; Paternoster & Iovanni, 1986; Paternoster, Saltzman, Waldo, & Chiricos, 1983; Tyler, 1990). This core premise of deterrence models is supported by many, but not all, studies examining the factors that shape people’s law-related behavior (Nagin, 1998; Tyler, 1990). Studies of deterrence also point to several factors that limit the likely effec- tiveness of deterrence models of social regulation. Perhaps the key factor limiting the value of deterrence strategies is the consistent finding that deterrence effects, when they are found, are small in magnitude. For example, in a review of studies of deterrence in the area of drug use, MacCoun (1993) finds that around 5% of the variance in drug use behavior can be explained by variations in the expected likelihood and/or severity of punishment. This suggests that much of the variance in law-related behavior flows from other factors besides risk estimates. Some of the difficulties associated with deterrence approaches are the result of the fact, established by deterrence research (see Nagin, 1998), that it is the perception of the certainty of punishment, rather than its severity, that most strongly shapes behavior. One consequence of this is that deterrence approaches are costly, because certainty of punishment is shaped by the deployment of police resources. Political leaders are attracted to severe punishments, such as the death penalty, in part because it is not expensive to implement such policies. Unfortunately, from a cost perspective, these severe punishments are not especially effective deterrents of crime (see Ellsworth & Gross, 1994). Given the realities of democratic societies, in which policing and surveillance are low, the probability of being detected when breaking many laws is low (Tyler, 1990). This makes deterrence based upon the probability of being detected for wrongdoing a poor strategy under many circumstances. To have a more effective strategy for dealing with the issue of public compli- ance, we would benefit from being in a situation in which people have additional reasons for obeying the law beyond their fear of being caught and punished for wrongdoing (Sherman, 1993, 1998, 1999; Tyler, 1990). It is to such additional mo- tivations that procedural justice approaches are directed. This need for additional Restorative Justice and Procedural Justice 311 motivations has also been recognized in recent discussions of deterrence theory, which include extralegal factors such as morality and informal social control (see Foglia, 1997; Grasmic & Bursik, 1990; Nagin & Pogarsky, 2001). Internal Motivations Lewin contrasts the influence of external contingencies to the influence of internal motivations (Gold, 1999). There are many types of internal motivations. One set is linked to things that people want to do—i.e., to their attitudes. For example, people are intrinsically motivated to engage in actions that they enjoy. Further, people are motivated to act on behalf of groups and people to whom they feel committed. The second set of internal motivations is linked to feelings of social obligation. These motivations reflect people’s willingness to act based on feelings of social values that reflect feelings of social responsibility. Two such values are important: legitimacy and morality (Tyler & Blader, 2005). Legitimacy from this social value perspective is the property that a rule or an authority has when others feel obligated to voluntarily defer to that rule or authority (Tyler, 1990, 2006). In other words, a legitimate authority is an authority regarded by people as entitled to have their decisions and rules accepted and followed by others (French & Raven, 1959). The roots of the modern discussion of legitimacy are usually traced by the important writings of Weber on authority and the social dynamics of authority (Weber, 1968). Weber argues that the ability to issue commands that will be obeyed does not rest solely upon the possession and ability to use power. In addition, there are rules that people will voluntary obey, and authorities whose directives will be voluntarily followed. Legitimacy, therefore, is a quality possessed by an authority, a law, or an institution that leads others to feel obligated to obey its decisions and directives. It is “a quality attributed to a regime by a population (Merelman, 1966, p. 548).” This feeling of responsibility reflects a willingness to suspend personal con- siderations of self-interest and to ignore personal moral values because a person thinks that an authority or a rule is entitled to determine appropriate behavior within a given situation or situations. Kelman and Hamilton (1989) refer to legitimacy as “authorization” to reflect the idea that a person authorizes an authority to determine appropriate behavior within some situation, and then feels obligated to follow the directives or rules that authority establishes. As they indicate, the authorization of actions by authorities “seem[s] to carry automatic justification for them. Behaviorally, authorization obviates the necessity of making judgments or choices. Not only do normal moral principles become inoperative, but—particularly when the actions are explicitly ordered—a different type of morality, linked to the duty to obey superior orders, tends to take over (Kelman & Hamilton, 1989, p. 16).” 312 Tyler One way to think about legitimacy is as a property of an institution or group of authorities. For example, studies of confidence in government ask people to rate the overall government, and its institutions and authorities. Studies of the legitimacy of legal authorities similarly ask people to evaluate their general feelings of responsibility and obligation to obey the law and legal authorities (see Tyler, 1990). Does the social value of legitimacy matter? Tyler (1990) examined this issue in a study of the law-related behavior and found that legitimacy shaped everyday compliance with the law, a conclusion supported by more recent studies (Sunshine & Tyler, 2003a). Further, legitimacy had more influence on compliance than did sanction risks. Hence, evidence suggests that internal values, at least the internal value of legitimacy, shape law-related behavior (Tyler, 1990; Tyler & Huo, 2002). So, our ability to shape such behavior would improve if we could understand how to activate these motivations. One way to encourage people to view law as legitimate is for legal authori- ties to act in procedurally just ways. For example, studies suggest that procedural justice during personal experiences with authorities is important because it builds the social value of legitimacy (Tyler, 2004). Legitimacy, once activated, then en- courages everyday compliance with the law. Hence, legal authorities receive more citizen cooperation when people generally view them as legitimate. People, who have more supportive social values, are easier for legal authorities to deal with during personal encounters. Beyond particular experiences, people are generally more likely to regard the police as legitimate if they believe that the police exercise their authority through fair procedures (Sunshine & Tyler, 2003a; Tyler, 2001). As people develop sup- portive social values such as legitimacy, they are more willing to defer to particular legal authorities (Tyler & Huo, 2002), and also generally more compliant with the law (Sunshine & Tyler, 2003a; Tyler, 1990). These general procedural justice judg- ments are more central to legitimacy than are evaluations of the effectiveness of the police in combating crime. The discussion of legitimacy makes clear that people’s internal values have an important role in shaping their behavior. Hence, the legal system gains when those values are engaged and support self-regulatory or internal motivations toward complying with the law and with the directives of legal authorities. To encourage such a value-based reaction to authorities, it is important for the police and courts to act in ways that people view as reflecting procedural justice. This focus on the importance of legitimacy reflects the legacy of Weber (1968), who was concerned with the circumstances under which people follow the direc- tives of social rules and social authorities. Legitimacy is important to the success of such authorities because they are enabled to gain public deference to a range of decisions by virtue of their social role. This deference is not unlimited, because legitimacy may exist within a certain sphere, but within that sphere, acceptance of Restorative Justice and Procedural Justice 313 the right of authorities to make decisions that ought to be accepted and obeyed is broad. Experiencing procedural justice, either in particular personal experience or in the everyday functioning of the law, is important because it encourages feelings of responsibility and obligation to follow the law—i.e., it increases the legitimacy of the law and the legal system. Hence, procedural justice suggests that possibility of a legal system based more heavily upon voluntary cooperation—of process- based regulation (Tyler & Huo, 2002; Tyler & Sunshine, 2003a). The Morality of the Law Legitimacy is not the only social value upon which the legal system might potentially be based. A second social value is personal morality—the motivation to behave in accord with one’s sense of what is appropriate and right to do in a given situation. For example, people may think that using drugs is morally right or wrong, irrespective of whether drug use is illegal. These feelings about the morality of particular behaviors also shape people’s behavior, with people being less motivated to act in ways that they think are immoral irrespective of whether those behaviors are or are not legal (Tyler, 1990). And, like the social value of legitimacy, morality is internal and shapes actions distinct from consideration of being caught and punished for wrongdoing (Tyler, 1990). What unites the study of legitimacy and morality? In both cases, the key is that people accept as their own feelings of responsibility and obligation for their actions in society. The influence of moral values is based on the internalization of feelings of responsibility to follow principles of personal morality (see Robinson & Darley, 1995; Tyler & Darley, 2000). A core element of moral values is that people feel a personal responsibility to follow those values, and feel guilty when they fail to do so. Hence, moral values, once they exist are self-regulatory in character, and those who have such values are personally motivated to bring their conduct into line with their moral standards. The importance of morality is central to the work of the psychologist Freud and the sociologist Durkheim (Tyler & Sunshine, 2003b). As Hoffman notes: “The legacy of both Sigmund Freud and Emile Durkheim is the agreement among so- cial scientists that most people do not go through life viewing society’s moral norms as external, coercively imposed pressures to which they must submit. Though the norms are initially external to the individual and often in conflict with [a person’s] desires, the norms eventually become part of [a person’s] inter- nal motive system and guide [a person’s] behavior even in the absence of external authority. Control by others is thus replaced by self-control [through a process labeled internalization] (Hoffman, 1977, p. 85).” Here the self-control of con- cern is reflected in the influence of one’s own internal moral values on one’s behavior. 314 Tyler As with Weber, the key issue addressed by Durkheim and Freud is the personal taking on of internal values that become self-regulating, so that people acknowl- edge and act on internal values that lead to deference to society, social rules, and authorities. However, in this case the values taken on are personal moral values—a responsibility to act in accord with ethical judgments about what is right and what is wrong. Although personal moral values may reflect the values of institutions and authorities with whom one deals, particularly during moral socialization during childhood, those values become internalized and viewed as one’s own personal values. After that time, they are followed for internal reasons, like the value of legitimacy. The distinction between legitimacy and morality is that, in the case of morality, legal authorities gain support for particular laws or decisions when those laws or decisions are in accord with people’s personal morality. Hence, the motivation to behave in ways that are moral does not lead to support the rule of law when the public thinks that the law is inconsistent with their morality. To activate the motivation force of morality, legal authorities must be pursuing policies that are consistent with people’s moral values (Sunshine & Tyler, 2003b). Of course, morality and legitimacy can be in conflict. A conflict between legitimacy and morality can occur with mundane and everyday practices, as when the government seems to criminalize drug use or certain sexual practices without the support of public morality (Darley, Tyler, & Bilz, 2003), or it can involve dramatic and high-stakes conflicts, as when the government seeks to compel people to serve in wars they think are unjust, or to pay taxes to support policies they view as immoral. Unlike legitimacy, morality is not linked to the role of the authority, and its independent roots in personal ethical values mean that, while morality usually supports following laws (Tyler, 1990), the two internal forces do not always support one another. The procedural justice approach seeks to activate morality through the fair exercise of authority. When people view the authorities as engaging in practices that the public views as being morally appropriate, that heightens their sense that legal authorities are behaving morally (Tyler & Blader, 2005). In other words, one important set of moral values is concerned with how the police should exercise their authority, so the procedures by which the police act communicate to members of the public whether the police share their moral values (Sunshine & Tyler, 2003b). For example, when the police engage in racial profiling, which people view as an unfair procedure, they diminish their moral authority by showing that they do not share the public’s moral values about how the police should act (Tyler & Wakslak, 2004). Legal authorities, in other words, can demonstrate that they share public morality by acting in ways that are consistent with public views about how to fairly exercise authority—e.g., by using fair procedures to make decisions. The activation of morality also occurs in two other ways that are not re- lated to procedural justice. First, by seeking to heighten the role of morality in Restorative Justice and Procedural Justice 315 shaping people’s behavior. The psychological literature on moral development, for example, focuses on strategies for internalizing moral values in children, whose adult behavior is then shaped by their moral judgments (Eisenberg, Reykowski, & Staub, 1989; Kurtines & Gewirtz, 1984; Lickona, 1976; Rest, 1986). The lit- erature on moral development suggests that most children develop moral values, but that development is not inevitable and it is possible for adults not to develop moral values during childhood. Hence, the degree to which a child develops moral values, which shape their adult behavior, has implications for the functioning of the law. The law can also enlist people’s moral values as a motivational force support- ing deference to the law by pursuing ends that people view as moral. For example, Robinson and Darley (1995) point to discrepancies—real and imagined—between the law and people’s moral values. They argue that the law is less likely to be able to call upon people’s moral motivations to support the legal system when its values are viewed as discrepant from those of the public. Hence, the law can engage moral values when and if the law is consistent with the moral values held by the public (Tyler, 2005). Procedural Justice and Restorative Justice The procedural justice approach shares a core similarity with the restorative justice approach. The restorative justice approach argues that the goal when deal- ing with people who may have broken social rules should be to seek ways to heighten the future motivations that those people have to engage psychologically and behaviorally in society. This engagement includes developing or becoming more committed to social values that promote self-regulation, and consequently adhering more closely to laws and social regulations in the future. In other words, both approaches view one important goal when dealing with people as being to create better community members. Restorative justice argues that the social goal that should dominate reactions to transgressions is to resolve the dispute via reintegrative shaming (Braithwaite, 2002). Reintegrative shaming combines strong disapproval of bad conduct with respect for the person who committed those bad acts. The goal is restoring victims, offenders, and the community. In the case of offenders, the goal is to encourage feelings of shame regarding one’s bad acts, accepting responsibility, and sincerely apologizing. This restores the dignity of offenders. Key to this process is the social connection that people feel to their family, friends, and community. These parties are present at restorative justice hearings, along with the victim and their family and friends. All of those present are involved in reconnecting the offender to their sense of responsibility to their community. The goal of this reconnection is to encourage feelings of responsibility to family, friends, and community that will enhance commitment to self-regulatory actions. This commitment, in turn, works against future transgressions of the law. 316 Tyler This restorative justice argument mirrors the concern in procedural justice research with developing informal and formal legal procedures that have the effect of strengthening the influence of social values on people’s law-related behavior. This can occur because people become more connected to their feelings of re- sponsibility to others in their community, because they become more motivated to follow their moral principles, or because they feel greater obligation to defer to societal authorities and institutions. All of these internal motivations facilitate future law abidingness. The influence of morality and legitimacy on law-related behavior has already been noted (Tyler, 1990). This influence supports the argument that procedural justice influences law-abiding behavior. Evidence also supports the facilitative role of restorative justice conferences (Sherman, 1999). Studies suggest that, at least with some types of crimes, experiencing a restorative justice conference leads to greater deference to law in the future (Nugent, Williams, & Umbreit, 2003; Paulson, 2003). This suggests that such conferences build internal motivation to accept the law and the decisions of legal authorities. The Mechanisms Involved While each of the three approaches outlined seeks to active people’s internal motivations, there are important differences in the focus of these three bodies of research. The procedural justice approach seeks to activate feelings of respon- sibility and obligation to authorities. Research makes clear that people feel that authorities are entitled to be obeyed when they exercise their authority using fair procedures (Tyler, 1990). Further, the use of fair procedures leads people to feel that the authorities share their moral values (Sunshine & Tyler, 2003b). In both cases, the key psychological mechanism is the activation of internal social values, which then motivate self-regulatory behavior. The moral value literature focuses on the development of strong moral values during the childhood socialization process. Those values then guide adult actions, leading people to be motivated to engage in actions that are consistent with their moral values. When they fail to do so, they feel the emotion of guilt. Guilt arises when one has engaged in actions inconsistent with one’s self-image (Tangney & Dearing, 2002). Finally, the restorative justice approach focuses on engaging people’s feelings of responsibility to their family and community. It argues that when people feel that they have damaged their image in the eyes of others, this has destructive consequences for themselves. People feel the damaging emotion of shame (Ahmed, Harris, Braithwaite, & Braithwaite, 2001; Scheff, 1997). By seeking to separate out and repair the damaged self while condemning the destructive action, the restorative conference has the goal of building positive connections to one’s family, friends, and community. Those social bonds then sustain ongoing motivations to Restorative Justice and Procedural Justice 317 engage in socially appropriate behaviors that earn the approval of others (Tangrey & Dearing, 2002). Hence, each of these models views an important goal as being to find ways to encourage desirable social behavior in the long term by activating people’s internal self-regulatory motivations. Irrespective of whether the relevant motivations are obligation to authorities, responsibility for following moral values, or social bonds with others, each provides the basis upon which a self-regulatory society can be developed. Of course, obligation, shame, and guilt are not identical psychological moti- vations, and one question is whether one approach is more efficacious than others. Empirical research has not compared these various models, either to see if one is more influential than others or to explore whether they are separate psychologi- cal dynamics. The psychological mechanisms underlying the models underlined are generally unexamined in the literature. It is clearer that these approaches are effective than it is why they are effective. Changing the Culture of Social Control Irrespective of which of these models is the focus of concern, the general message is the same. The current focus on punishment as a mechanism through which to shape the behavior of both wrongdoers and people in general has had negative effects on society, particularly American society. It has led to a dramatic growth in the American prison population, and soured the relationship between the law, legal authorities, and members of society. It has had a particularly negative impact on the minority community. The goal of the procedural justice model, like the restorative model, is to articulate a different approach to managing issues of social order and social control. Both models, like the moral socialization model, argue that most people have social values and social bonds that motivate them to follow most rules most of the time. It is this motivational force that generally sustains societies, freeing legal authorities to focus on managing that small subset of people who lack such values and ties (Ayres & Braithwaite, 1992). The procedural justice model focuses on everyday rule following. It suggests that the key to motivating compliance based on internal social values is to maintain the legitimacy of the law and of legal authorities. To do so, legal authorities need to focus on exercising legal authority fairly. That procedural fairness encourages people to feel that the law is legitimate and ought to be obeyed. As a consequence, people become self-regulatory, and follow the law as a consequence of their own internal values (Tyler, 2005, 2006; Tyler & Blader, 2005). In addition, the procedural justice model has implications for people’s personal experiences with law. When people come before the law, for example, because they have broken some law and appear in court or deal with a police officer, there are 318 Tyler several goals that are important. One is to deal with appropriate punishment or restitution. The other, emphasized by the procedural justice model, is to encourage feelings of legitimacy among those dealing with the legal system. In other words, each encounter that people have with authorities is an instance of civic education, which teaches people about the law. Evidence suggests that even when people are being sanctioned by the law, they are also being educated about the nature of the law and legal authorities (Tyler & Huo, 2002). One of the most striking examples of the procedural justice approach is pro- vided by Paternoster, Brame, Bachman, and Sherman (1997). This study examines the long-term consequences of people’s experiences with the police when the po- lice are called to deal with domestic violence complaints. In such situations, the police direct their actions toward the offender—typically the man in the situation. But, what actions matter in the long term? The findings of this study suggest that if the police treat the offender fairly, that person is likely to refrain from further abuse in the future. In other words, the police can motivate people to self-regulate in the future by treating them with fairness when they deal with them. This study illustrates the paradigm underlying the procedural justice approach. It suggests the possibility of process-based regulation. By using fair processes, the police encourage the activation of the social values that sustain law-abiding behav- ior over time. In addition, as Tyler and Huo (2002) demonstrate, fair procedures encourage immediate deference, lessen the likelihood of spirals of conflict, and increase the legitimacy of the police and courts. Hence, fair procedures have both immediate and long-term positive consequences. One concern about the range of the procedural justice approach is whether or not it applies to the poor, the disenfranchised, and those who are less likely to buy into societies’ values. Tyler and Huo (2002) address this question directly by comparing the reactions of white and minority members of the public to their personal experiences with the police and courts. They find that the procedural justice model is an equally strong predictor of reactions within both groups. In fact, although there are large race-based differences in reactions to the police and courts, those differences disappear when procedural justice variables are included in the model. Further, Tyler and Huo (2002) look specifically at the group of respondents typically considered most problematic by law enforcement—young, minority, males—and find that the members of this group are also strongly moti- vated by procedural justice judgments. Like the procedural justice model, the restorative justice model also deals with legal procedures that are initiated when someone breaks a legal rule. And the goal of restorative procedures is also to further people’s loyalty to and adherence with legal rules in the future. In the case of restorative justice, the restorative justice conference seeks to motivate such immediate and future behavior by separating the “good” person from their “bad” conduct. The conferences then seek to both deal with the consequences of the bad conduct and, separately, to connect the good Restorative Justice and Procedural Justice 319 person to their motivation to behave in ways that win respect from their family, friends, and community. It is this connection with one’s favorable self-image that motivates compliance in the future. Hence, both of these models argue for the possibility of a society that focuses on punishing wrongdoing, but upon creating and maintaining people who are motivated by their own internal values and social bonds to self-regulate. As Tyler and Huo (2002) argue, the success of such efforts builds momentum over time. They demonstrate that those people who view the law as legitimate respond to that view by evaluating their personal experiences with the police and courts in more process-oriented ways. Hence, the existence of legitimacy makes it easier for policing to occur based upon the use of fair procedures. This, in turn, further enhances the possibility of creating legitimacy. Many of the ideas outlined here are not only implications of a procedural justice or restorative justice approach to policing. They are also part of the com- munity policing and problem-oriented policing approaches to policing. Those ap- proaches emphasize police efforts to move beyond reacting to already committed crimes to making efforts to proactively work with communities to solve community problems. Studies suggest that people value having the police talk to citizens and coop- erate with citizens to solve community problems (Sunshine & Tyler, 2003a). They support more bike and pedestrian patrols because they “like to perceive the police as friends and helpers and they would support endeavors to improve the work of the police force much in the sense of what community and problem-oriented policing propose (Weitekamp, Kerner, & Meier, 1996, p. 16).” Similarly a study of public complaints about the police similarly showed that the two primary reasons for complaining were “rude, arrogant, unfriendly, over-casual treatment (38%)” and “unreasonable, unfair behavior (46%)” (see Skogan, 1994). These findings suggest that people would like to improve the relationship be- tween citizens and the police, a core concern of problem-oriented and community policing. In fact, Weitekamp et al. (1996) propose a restorative problem-solving police prevention program that views reconciliation between victims, the commu- nity as a whole, and perpetrators as a key goal. They argue that four groups—the police, the community, the offender, and the victim—should be involved in ef- forts to reconcile following wrongdoing. All of these groups should be jointly concerned to make their community safer, reduce fear, prevent future crime, im- prove the quality of life, and increase interpersonal harmony among the people in communities. The comparison of these approaches makes clear that there are several con- ceptual issues underlying the distinctions among restorative, problem-oriented, and community policing. One issue is what the appropriate responsibilities of the police should be. Traditionally the police are responsible for enforcing the law by regulating public behavior and apprehending those who break laws. Those people 320 Tyler are evaluated and potentially punished by the courts. Recently there have been ar- guments for an expanded police role in helping to solve community problems, and help communities to solidify themselves as communities. These arguments stem in part from the recognition that the police cannot effectively control crime with- out community assistance (Sampson & Bartusch, 1998; Sampson, Raudenbush, & Earls, 1997), and in part from the suggestion that at least some members of the public would like for the police to have a broader role in the community than just rule enforcement and crime control. A second issue is who should deal with rule breaking. Within modern societies, the state has the central authority for deciding how to react to rule breaking, with the police and courts deciding who to arrest, how to determine wrongdoing, and how to punish for wrongdoing. This has led to a variety of types of discontent. The victims of crime feel excluded from the determination of punishment, and would like to have a greater role in deciding how to deal with criminals. Communities would also like a greater role in part, because they feel that the punishments of the formal legal system depart from the communities’ feelings about what is right and what is wrong (Robinson & Darley, 1995). These groups have argued for greater opportunities to participate in determinations of how to deal with crime and criminals. Finally, there is the question of how crime should be dealt with. The current legal system emphasizes determinations of guilt and the application of punishment. However, approaches such as the restorative justice model argue for the value of seeking to rehabilitate offenders—emphasizing the encouragement of future law-abiding behavior as the goal over punishment for past wrongs. This goal leads to efforts to work with the families and communities affected by the crime to encourage the criminal to come into compliance with community norms and values. Restorative justice itself is a model for the goal that should shape reactions to wrongdoing. It does not speak to the issue of who—the community, the police, the courts—should have the authority to manage responses to deviant behavior. In a series of experiments conducted in Australia, for example, the police managed restorative justice sessions (Braithwaite, 1989, 2002). However, in many of the traditional dispute resolution approaches from which restorative justice draws its inspiration, the community and community leaders were the key authorities. The restorative justice approach is a model for how to react to wrongdoing, rather than a model of policing, but it can be applied to policing if the police adopt a restorative justice approach to their dealings with wrongdoers. Procedural justice does not focus on shame. It focuses on obligation and re- sponsibility. However, both shame and obligation are internal motivations for self- regulatory behavior. In fact, we can combine these with a third motivation noted earlier in the discussion—morality—to identify three self-regulatory motivations. These are shown in Table 1. While all three are united in their goal of activating people’s internal values, they focus on different issues. Procedural justice focuses Restorative Justice and Procedural Justice 321 Table 1. Self-regulatory Motivations. Model Focus Motivation that is activated Procedural justice models Legitimacy Obligation of authority Restorative justice models Relationships to Shame others Moral development models Principles of Guilt right and wrong on feelings of obligation and responsibility to authorities. Restorative justice is concerned with people’s relationships to others and the shame that occurs when people disappoint others. Moral values lead to guilt when a person violates their own personal standards of right and wrong. In contrast, sanction-based approaches undermine and lessen the influence of people’s values on their behavior. Social psychologists make clear that one consequence of focusing on incentives and sanctions within a given situation is that people’s behavior becomes more strongly linked to those instrumental factors. If people have internal motivations, such as social values, the role of those values in shaping the behavior is “crowded out,” and becomes less important (Deci, 1975; Frey, 1994). In the long run, the use of sanction-based approaches has the consequence of undermining the influence of social values on behavior. The use of sanctions today means that greater and more frequent sanction use will be required in the future. Can These Models Be Implemented? As noted at the beginning of this discussion, there is evidence that these models can be effective. But, can they be implemented? One problem that might lie in the way are public views about how to respond to wrongdoing. These views are linked to public judgments about whether people can be changed and, if so, how best to achieve change. In the 1960s, there was a strong belief that people could be rehabilitated (Tyler et al., 1997). However, the greater punitiveness already noted might suggest that this belief has changed among Americans. Tyler and Boeckmann (1997) found that people in a sample of Californi- ans indicated that they did not feel that people could be changed when they felt that wrongdoers lacked core moral and social values and social bonds that could be appealed to and activated among wrongdoers. The feeling that there were no 322 Tyler Table 2. What Policies Are Effective in Lowering Crime? Yes (%) Will this policy Be Effective in Lowering Crime Putting criminals in prison for life after three felonies. 55 Using the death penalty more often? 44 Publishing names of criminals in their communities so that their neighbors and friends are aware of their crimes? 70 Requiring people to apologize? 51 Using schools to encourage the development of values such as respect and responsibility to follow rules? 85 Is it difficult to rehabilitate burglars who commit property crimes? 76 Is it difficult to rehabilitate violent offenders? 95 common core values or social bonds shared by wrongdoers and others in the com- munity, when found, was linked to the view that American society has become culturally diverse. This belief was also linked to support for the punitive “three strikes” law, which is a clear alternative view to the idea of rehabilitation and restoration. Hence, one aspect of the challenge posed by restorative justice is to educate the public to the feasibility of these approaches to managing wrongdoing. How serious was this potential problem? To address this question, we can look at the results of interviews of Californians conducted by Tyler and Boeckmann (1997). Those interviews were conducted in the wake of the passage of the “three strikes” initiative, a punitive measure mandating life in prison for three felony convictions. Do the views of those in this sample support the argument that people do not believe in the possibility of rehabilitation? Interestingly no. People were asked that question, as well as several related other questions on what works. Their answers are shown in Table 2. They indicate that people generally think that shaming and moral education are the most effective ways to control crime. It is striking that people, while they may support punitive measures, do not view them as particularly effective. Hence, if they felt that the conditions were such that rehabilitation and moral education were possible, people would support those approaches as being more effective. The question that we might best ask is why people do or do not think that these different approaches are effective. Table 3 looks at the role of whether people think that there is a sense of obligation to obey the law, trust in legal authorities, moral values, and social bonds on whether they think that different approaches to dealing with crime are effective. The results suggest that people think rehabilitation will work if people have shared moral values and if they think that people trust legal authorities. They think that shaming works when there are shared social bonds, shared moral values, and feelings of obligation to obey the law. They believe that moral education works when people have shared moral values. And they think that punishment is more effective when people share moral values and social bonds, and feel an obligation to obey the law. Restorative Justice and Procedural Justice 323 Table 3. What Shapes Whether Punishment Works? Is Moral Is Punishment Is Shaming Is Rehabilitation Education Effective? Effective? Effective? Effective? Do moral values exist in the community? .39∗∗∗ .18∗ .26∗∗∗ .24∗∗∗ Do social bonds exist in the community? .20∗∗ .15∗ .08 .09 Are legal authorities trusted? .05 .01 .21∗∗∗ −.04 Do people feel obligated to obey the law? .15∧ .17∗ .05 .00 Adj. R2 21%∗∗∗ 10%∗∗∗ 13%∗∗∗ 4%∗∗∗ ∧p < .10; ∗p < .05; ∗∗p < .01; ∗∗∗p < .001. These findings reinforce the idea that people are punitive not because they feel it is an optimal strategy. Rather, they think that the strategies outlined by the procedural justice and restorative justice models are more likely to be effective in reducing the problem of crime. That effectiveness, however, depends on the exis- tence of shared moral values, shared social ties, and feelings of trust, confidence, and obligation toward law. Hence, one strategy is to communicate the findings outlined above, studies showing that procedural and restorative approaches do work. Summary The challenge for the future is to reverse an alarming trend in societies’ ap- proaches to wrongdoing. That trend is to be increasingly punitive and preoccupied with punishment for wrongdoing. This trend is especially troubling because in earlier eras the focus of much of the effort when dealing with wrongdoing was upon the rehabilitation of offenders. The procedural justice and restorative justice approaches share the underlying belief that people can be rehabilitated and that society and the legal system have a great deal to gain from focusing on the possi- bilities of rehabilitation and the restoration of people as law-abiding members of society. Further, both models have provided compelling empirical evidence in sup- port of their arguments. These findings aside, it is clear that efforts to change the current paradigm for dealing with wrongdoing must involve substantial changes in public views about both society and human motivation. References Ahmed, E., Harris, N., Braithwaite, J., & Braithwaite, V. (2001). Shame management through reinte- gration. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Ayres, I., & Braithwaite, J. (1992). Responsive regulation: Transcending the deregulation debate. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Braithwaite, J. (1989). Crime, shame, and reintegration. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. 324 Tyler Braithwaite, J. (2002). Restorative justice and responsive regulation. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Darley, J., Tyler, T. R., & Bilz, K. (2003). Enacting justice: The interplay of individual and institutional perspectives. In M. A. Hogg & J. Cooper (Eds.), Handbook of social psychology. London: Sage. Deci, E. L. (1975). Intrinsic motivation. New York: Plenum. Eisenberg, N., Reykowski, J., & Staub, E. (1989). Social and moral values. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Ellsworth, P. C., & Gross, S. R. (1994). Hardening of the attitudes: Americans’ views on the death penalty. Journal of Social Issues, 50, 19–52. Foglia, W. C. (1997). Perceptual deterrence and the mediating effect of internalized norms among inner-city teenagers. Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency, 34, 414–443. French, J. R. P., & Raven, B. (1959). The bases of social power. In D. Cartwright (Ed.), Studies in social power. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. Frey, B. S. (1994). How intrinsic motivation is crowded in and out. Rationality and Society, 6, 334–352. Garland, D. (2001). The culture of control: Crime and social order in contemporary society. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Gold, M. (1999). The complete social scientist: A Kurt Lewin reader. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. Grasmick, H. G., & Bursik, R. J. (1990). Conscience, significant others, and rational choice. Law and Society Review, 24, 837–861. Haney, C., & Zimbardo, P. (1998). The past and future of U.S. prison policy: Twenty-five years after the Stanford Prison Experiment. American Psychologist, 53, 709–727. Hoffman, M. L. (1977). Moral internalization: Current theory and research. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 10, 85–133. Kelman, H. C., & Hamilton, V. L. (1989). Crimes of obedience. New Haven, CT: Yale. Kurtines, W. M., & Gewirtz, J. L. (1984). Morality, moral behavior, and moral development. New York: Wiley. Lickona, T. (1976). Moral development and behavior. New York: Holt, Rinehart, Winston. MacCoun, R. J. (1993). Drugs and the law: A psychological analysis of drug prohibition. Psychological Bulletin, 113, 497–512. Meares, T. L. (2000). Norms, legitimacy, and law enforcement. Oregon Law Review, 79, 391–415. Merelman, R. J. (1966). Learning and legitimacy. American Political Science Review, 60, 548– 561. Nagin, D. S. (1998). Criminal deterrence research at the outset of the twenty-first century. In M. Tonry (Ed.), Crime and justice (Vol. 23, pp. 1–42). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Nagin, D. S., & Paternoster, R. (1991). The preventive effects of the perceived risk of arrest. Crimi- nology, 29, 561–585. Nagin, D. S., & Pogarsky, G. (2001). Integrating celerity, impulsivity and extralegal sanction threats into a model of general deterrence. Criminology, 39, 865–892. Nugent, W. R., Williams, M., & Umbreit, M. S. (2003). Participation in victim-offender mediation and the prevalence and severity of subsequent delinquent behavior. Utah Law Review, 2003(1), 137–166. Paternoster, R. (1987). The deterrent effect of the perceived certainty and severity of punishment. Justice Quarterly, 4, 173–217. Paternoster, R. (1989). Decisions to participate in and desist from four types of common delinquency. Law and Society Review, 23, 7–40. Paternoster, R., Brame, R., Bachman, R., & Sherman, L. W. (1997). Do fair procedures matter?: The effect of procedural justice on spouse assault. Law and Society Review, 31, 163–204. Paternoster, R., & Iovanni, L. (1986). The deterrent effect of perceived severity. Social Forces, 64, 751–777. Paternoster, R., Saltzman, L. E., Waldo, G. P., & Chiricos, T. G. (1983). Perceived risk and social control: Do sanctions really deter? Law and Society Review, 17, 457–479. Poulson, B. (2003). A third voice: A review of empirical research on the psychological outcomes of restorative justice. Utah Law Review, 2003(1), 167–204. Reiss, A. (1971). The police and the public. New Haven, CT: Yale. Rest, J. R. (1986). Moral development: Advances in research and theory. New York: Praeger. Restorative Justice and Procedural Justice 325 Roberts, J. V., & Stalans, L. J. (2000). Public opinion, crime, and criminal justice. Boulder, CO: Westview. Robinson, P. H., & Darley, J. (1995). Justice, liability, and blame. Boulder, CO: Westview. Sampson, R. J., & Bartusch, D. J. (1998). Legal cynicism and (subcultural?) tolerance of deviance. Law and Society Review, 32, 777–804. Sampson, R. J., Raudenbush, S. W., & Earls, F. (1997). Neighborhoods and violent crime. Science, 277, 918–924. Scheff, T. J. (1997). Emotions, the social bond, and human reality. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge Uni- versity Press. Sherman, L. (1993). Defiance, deterrence, irrelevance: A theory of the criminal sanction. Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency, 30, 445–473. Sherman, L. (1998). Alternative prevention strategies and the role of policing. Presentation at a con- ference on “Beyond incarceration.” Cambridge, MA: Harvard Trade Union Program. Sherman, L. (1999). Consent of the governed. Presentation at Hebrew University. Skogan, W. G. (1994). Contacts between police and public. London: A home office research and planning unit report. Sunshine, J., & Tyler, T. R. (2003a). The role of procedural justice and legitimacy in shaping public support for policing. Law and Society Review, 37, 555–589. Sunshine, J., & Tyler, T. R. (2003b). Moral solidarity, identification with the community, and the importance of procedural justice. Social Psychology Quarterly, 66, 153–165. Tangney, J. P., & Dearing, R. L. (2002). Shame and guilt. New York: Guilford. Tyler, T. R. (1990). Why people obey the law: Procedural justice, legitimacy, and compliance. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Tyler, T. R. (1997). Citizen discontent with legal procedures. American Journal of Comparative Law, 45, 869–902. Tyler, T. R. (1998). Public distrust of the law. University of Cincinnati Law Review, 66, 847–876. Tyler, T. R. (2001). Public trust and confidence in legal authorities. Behavioral Sciences and the Law, 19, 215–235. Tyler, T. R. (2003). Procedural justice, legitimacy, and the effective rule of law. In M. Tonry (Ed.), Crime and justice: A review of research (pp. 283–358). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Tyler, T. R. (2004). Procedural justice. In A. Sarat (Ed.), The Blackwell companion to law and society (pp. 435–452). Malden, MA: Blackwell. Tyler, T. R. (2006). Legitimacy and legitimation. Annual Review of Psychology, 57, 375– 400. Tyler, T. R. (2005). Promoting employee policy adherence and rule following in work settings: The value of self-regulatory approaches. Brooklyn Law Review, 70, 1287–1312. Tyler, T. R., & Blader, S. (2000). Cooperation in groups. Philadelphia: Psychology Press. Tyler, T. R., and Blader, S.L. (2005). Can businesses effectively regulate employee conduct?: The antecedents of rule following in work settings. Academy of Management Journal, 48, 1143– 1158. Tyler, T. R., & Boeckmann, R. J. (1997). Three strikes and you are out, but why? The psychology of public support for punishing rule breakers. Law and Society Review, 31, 237–265. Tyler, T. R., Boeckmann, R. J., Smith, H. J., & Huo, Y. J. (1997). Social justice in a diverse society. Boulder: Westview. Tyler, T. R., & Darley, J. (2000). Building a law abiding society. Hofstra Law Review, 28, 707– 739. Tyler, T. R., & Huo, Y. J. (2002). Trust in the law: Encouraging public cooperation with the police and courts. New York: Russell-Sage. Tyler, T. R., & Wakslak, C. (2004). Profiling and the legitimacy of the police: Procedural jus- tice, attributions of motive, and the acceptance of social authority. Criminology, 42, 13– 42. Weber, M. (1968). Economy and society. (G. Roth and C. Wittich, Eds.). Berkeley: University of California Press. Weitekamp, E. G. M., Kerner, H., & Meier, U. (1996). Problem solving policing. Paper, International Conference on Problem Solving Policing as Crime Prevention, Stockholm, Sweden. 326 Tyler Whitman, J. Q. (2003). Harsh justice: Criminal punishment and the widening divide between American and Europe. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. TOM R. TYLER is University Professor of Psychology at New York University. His research examines the dynamics of authority in groups and organizations. His books include: The Social Psychology of Procedural Justice (1988); Why People Obey the Law (1990); Social Justice in a Diverse Society (1997); and Trust in the Law (2002). work_4kite2kjdnbuxkar7ldfvqvriu ---- Unequal Opportunities and Distributive Justice Learning and Peer Effects Urs Fischbacher Gerald Eisenkopf Franziska Föllmi-Heusi Research Paper Series Thurgau Institute of Economics and Department of Economics at the University of Konstanz No. 57 september 2010 Unequal Opportunities and Distributive Justice http://nbn-resolving.de/urn:nbn:de:bsz:352-opus-124339 http://kops.ub.uni-konstanz.de/volltexte/2010/12433/ 1 Unequal Opportunities and Distributive Justice Gerald Eisenkopf Urs Fischbacher Franziska Föllmi-Heusi University of Konstanz & Thurgau Institute of Economics Post Box 131 78457 Konstanz Germany Contact: gerald.eisenkopf@uni-konstanz.de September 23, 2010 Abstract: There is well established empirical evidence that more redistribution occurs when luck rather than performance determines the earnings. We provide experimental evidence on how unequal access to performance enhancing education affects demand for redistribution. In this experiment, we can control the information about the role of luck and effort. We find that unequal opportunities evoke a preference for redistribution that is comparable to the situation when luck alone determines the allocation rather than performance. Furthermore, unequal opportunities reduce performance incentives. Keywords: Distribution, Inequality of opportunities, Negotiation, Education, Experiment JEL-Codes: D03, D31, I20 Acknowledgements: We thank Kate Bendrick, Lisa Bruttel, Simeon Schudy, Pascal Sulser and Verena Utikal and Seminar participants at the 2010 ESA World Meeting in Copenhagen for helpful comments. Anton Berwald provided excellent research assistance. The usual disclaimer applies 2 1 Introduction People are more willing to accept inequality in incomes if it results from hard work rather than pure luck1. Differences in education account for a substantial share of this inequality but survey studies cannot reveal if and how income differences derived from education transform into a demand for redistribution2. First, the roles of luck and hard work are ambiguous with respect to the access to education. Random processes like high innate abilities or a favorable socio-economic environment enhance the chances to get education but the student herself still has to provide effort in order to acquire and improve her skill. Second and perhaps more important, people differ substantially with respect to their beliefs about the impact of luck and effort on the access to education. Moreover, the beliefs often do not reflect the actual inequality in the access to education3. We investigate the demand for post-educational redistribution with a real-effort experiment that takes these problems into account. In our experiment, subjects are paired in groups of two. In the real effort-task, a quiz task, they create an output, which they contribute to a common pool. Then, they negotiate how to distribute their joint output. In all treatments, subjects get the opportunity to learn some of the questions of the quiz. Our focus is on the education treatment in which one of the two subjects in a group gets a better education because she can learn more relevant questions. One benchmark is the skill treatment in which a subject�’s contribution depends mostly on her ex-ante skills. In both treatments, a subject�’s contribution increased with the number of correctly answered general knowledge questions. Hence, knowledge was the relevant skill in this experiment. Since one randomly chosen subject in each group in the education treatment received additional knowledge it is obvious that luck was more relevant for contributions in this treatment than in the skill treatment. A second benchmark is provided by the luck treatment, in which a lottery only determines the contribution. In each treatment we provided all subjects with identical information. Compared to survey studies, our experiment has four main advantages. First, in the field, it is unclear which processes create the inequality. This implies in particular that one 1 See for example the studies by Hoffman et al. (1994) , Burrows and Loomes (1994) , Ruffle (1998) , Konow (2003), or Durante and Putterman (2009). 2 Educated people earn more money and receive higher nonmonetary rewards as well. Psacharopoulos and Patrinos (2004) provide a survey on the former and Grossman (2006) one on the latter issue. 3 Alesina and Glaeser (2005) show in a cross-country study that beliefs do not reflect the actual (in)equality of opportunities correctly. Instead, people may base their beliefs on personal experiences rather than on econometric studies (Piketty, 1995) and they may have a biased perception of these experiences (Benabou and Tirole, 2006) 3 does not know other peoples�’ beliefs about these processes. In our experiment there is common knowledge about the impact of random processes on allocations. Thus, the subjects in our experiment know the sources of inequality (luck, merit, inequality of opportunity). Second, subjects do not just state preferences for redistribution. They make actual distribution decisions. Third, by devising a rank order payment scheme we assured that the distribution of initial allocations is the same in all three treatments. In this way, we control for the possible confound that egalitarian societies may be less productive as the anticipation of high redistribution discourages contribution to the social output in the first place. Furthermore, the design ensures that participants have a comparable incentive to provide effort in all treatments. Fourth, the random assignment of subjects into treatment groups eliminates possible selection effects that would be present in the field. Our study takes two principles of distributive justice into account, an egalitarian one and a desert-based one. Strict egalitarianism �“advocates the allocation of equal material goods to all members of society�” (Lamont and Favor (2007) in the online version of the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy). According to the desert principle, people should be rewarded according to the value of their contribution to the social product4. Several studies have shown that people opt for more egalitarian distributions once luck rather than meritocratic criteria determine an outcome The desert-principle and similar meritocratic ideas include a concept of equality, meaning equality of opportunity rather than equality of outcome. A third fairness ideal, liberal egalitarianism, addresses inequality of outcomes. Similar to the accountability principle (J. Konow, 2000, 1996) liberal egalitarianism demands that distributions should depend on choices and decisions. If two people make the same choice in the same context, both should get the same reward even if the outcomes differ. Cappelen et al. (2007) investigate distribution decisions after an investment period with unequal rates of returns. They provide evidence for the application of all three fairness norms among their subjects. However, their experiment addresses the question on how inequality of opportunities affects redistribution decisions only in parts. For this question it is important to know whether the different fairness norms also prevail in situations with equal opportunities or purely randomly determined investments5. Such a comparison reveals whether people 4 It is important to distinguish between the desert principle and the provision of incentives. The latter implies a provision on the distribution of outcome before production has taken place while the former considers a distribution after production has taken place. 5 Inequity averse people in the sense of Fehr and Schmidt (1999) do not accept inequality in outcomes even if the differences depend on choices only. On the other hand, libertarian thinkers such as Hayek (1960) are reluctant to accept redistribution even if luck has a strong impact on economic outcomes. 4 make claims for more or less redistribution once they have correct information about the determinants of inequalities in opportunities. This comparison is particularly important in the context of inequalities in the access to education. Educational choices depend on skills (or abilities) which are, at least to a certain degree, exogenous, unobservable and unevenly distributed productivity factors6. Nevertheless, skill premiums are widely tolerated and meritocratic societies claim that the most able citizens do constitute their elite. We also provide a new perspective on the analysis of taxation in economies with unequal opportunities. Bovenberg and Jacobs (2005) claim that governments face a trade-off between equity and efficiency with respect to the financing of education. Subsidized education induces a more efficient labor supply but implies, ceteris paribus, redistribution from less intelligent, relatively poor individuals to smarter, richer ones. As a consequence, most developed economies use progressive taxation to mitigate income inequality in general, but they also subsidize education, even at highly selective universities. As mentioned above, any demand for redistribution depends on the beliefs about the roles of luck and effort in the generation of wealth, whether or not these beliefs are correct. Alesina and La Ferrara (2005) find that, in the United States at least, preferences for redistribution depend crucially on the individual belief in equal opportunity. Alesina and Angeletos (2005) show that international differences in beliefs about the source of inequality explain the differences in redistributive characteristics of tax regimes. The more people believe that luck determines income, the higher is the demand for redistribution. Our results show that subjects�’ responses to unequal learning opportunities are similar to their responses when luck alone determines output. Nevertheless, we find that the size of a subject�’s contribution has a significant impact on the allotment of the common pool. Unsurprisingly, these �“moral property rights�” (as in Gächter and Riedl (2005)) are particularly strong in the skill treatment but they are present even in the luck treatment.. We also observe that the differences in the bargaining behavior have an incentive effect, as subjects in the skill treatment produce more points than comparable subjects in the education treatment. These results suggest that full awareness about inequalities in opportunity makes people less productive and induces stronger claims for redistribution. The paper is structured as follows. The following section presents the experimental design. Afterwards we provide behavioral predictions. Section 4 presents the results of the experiment. Section 5 summarizes the paper and provides concluding comments. 6 Therefore, Bovenberg and Jacobs (2005) claim that governments face a trade-off between equity and efficiency with respect to the financing of education. Subsidized education induces a more efficient labor supply but implies, ceteris paribus, a redistribution from less intelligent, relatively poor individuals to smarter, richer ones 5 2 Experimental design In all treatments, we examine the negotiation of two group members about how to distribute a jointly owned common pool. There are three treatments, which differ in how the contribution to the common pool is determined: In the first treatment (the skill treatment), the individual contribution of a subject to the joint output was determined by her skills (more specifically her general knowledge). Also in the second treatment (the education treatment), skill determined output. However, in this treatment one randomly chosen member in the group had the opportunity to enhance her relevant skills relative to the other member. In the third treatment (the luck treatment), luck determined the individual contribution. The experiment included three different phases, a learning phase, a production and contribution phase, and a negotiation phase. Learning All subjects learned the correct answers for 60 knowledge questions. We used multiple choice versions of questions from the German standard version of the quiz game �“Trivial Pursuit�” which includes questions on geography, entertainment, history, arts and literature, science and technology as well as sports. Subjects they could display the correct answer of each question with a button. The treatments differed with respect to the number of questions a subject was familiar with from the learning phase. In the skill treatment, 5% of the questions from the learning period (i.e. 3 out of 60) reappeared in the production period. In the education treatment, one member in each group had learned 5% of the relevant questions while the other one had learned 95% (i.e. 57 out of 60 questions). In the luck treatment, each subject learned 50% of the relevant questions. In the skill and the luck treatment, the subjects were informed about the number of relevant questions at the beginning of the learning period. In the education treatment, the subjects were initially informed about the possible number of relevant questions. The actual assignment of the number of relevant questions and the information of the subjects occurred immediately after the learning period via the throw of a die. Production and contribution to the common pool In the production phase each subject had to answer 60 knowledge questions. In the production phase, the subjects could choose between 4 possible answers. Only one of the answers was correct. As Trivial Pursuit provides only the correct answers, the authors of this paper 6 developed the alternatives on their own. The experiment included two payment components. The first component was dependent on the own absolute performance. A subject received 0.2 points for a correct answer, with one point being the equivalent of 0.15 euro (about 0.23 US dollar at the time of the experiment). A wrong answer implied a loss of 0.2 points. The subjects could also choose to leave a question unanswered. But once the subjects had made their choice for a question they could not return to that question. An unanswered question did not affect the number of points. If more answers were wrong than right, the payment was deducted from the show-up fee of 4 euro. The second payment component was a subjects share from the common pool. The negotiation procedure will be discussed below. A subject´s contribution to the common pool was determined by the subject�’s rank among fellow participants in the session. In the skill and the education treatments, performance determined the rank, i.e., a more productive subject contributed more to the common pool. The subject with the lowest productivity in a session contributed 10 points, the subject with the second lowest productivity 20 points and so on. In sessions with 24 participants, the most productive participant contributed 240 points. We did not use the earned points as performance measure since it would be almost impossible to get comparable performance distributions across the treatments. In the luck treatment, in each session a two-stage random process determined the individual contributions of the 24 subjects to the common pool in their specific group. A die determined high (contribution > 120 points) and low contributors ( 120 Punkte). Half of the subjects were in either condition. Then, a lottery specified the actual size of the individual contributions7. The realizations were independent of the individual productivity. Hence, subjects in the luck treatment benefited from the production phase only via the income to their private account. After production, the subjects were matched into groups of two. In the skill treatment, the matching occurred at random. In the luck treatment, each group included one high contributor to the common pool and one low contributor. In the education treatment, one educated person was always matched with one uneducated person. The high differences in learned questions in this treatment ensured that all educated subjects were also high contributors. These groups now negotiated about the distribution of the common pool (see below). Table 1 summarizes the different treatments with respect to their characteristics in the learning and production phases. 7 120 points or less in the case of low contributors, 130 points or more in the case of high contributors. The possible contributions were ranked in steps of 10 points, with 10 as the lowest possible contribution and 240 as the highest possible one. 7 Table 1: The phases of the experiment and the experimental treatments Phases Skill Treatment Education Treatment Luck Treatment Learning (60 questions) 5% are relevant for production 5% are relevant for one group member 95% are relevant for the other group member 50% are relevant for production Production Private Benefit 60 questions to be answered 0.2 points reward for a correct answer. 0.2 points deduction for a wrong answer. Contribution to common pool The number of earned points influences the contribution Actual contribution between 10 and 240 according to a subject�’s productivity rank among the other subjects in the session Actual contribution between 10 and 240 according to a random process Matching into groups Random. We analyze groups with one high contributor (>120 points) and one low contributor ( 120 points) One educated person and one uneducated person. One high contributor (>120 points) and one low contributor ( 120 points) Negotiation Each group member makes a proposal and a minimum demand. One of the two proposals is selected. The proposal is accepted if it exceeds the other person�’s minimum demand. 8 Negotiation The negotiation procedure was identical in all treatments. At the beginning of the phase all subjects were informed about the size of the common pool and the share they contributed to it. After that, each subject decided as a proposer and as a demander. In the former role, the subject proposed how to distribute the common pool by allocating percentage points to herself and the other group member. As a demander, the subject stated the minimum share for herself for accepting the proposal of the other player. A random mechanism determined which player in the group was the proposer. If the allotted share to the demander matched or exceeded the stated minimum, the proposal was accepted and the pool divided accordingly. If the allotted share was below the demand the negotiation failed in this round. This also happened when the proposal of the other player would have been accepted. If the negotiation failed, the procedure was repeated with a smaller common pool. Six points were deducted from the common pool after each round with a failed negotiation. Again a random mechanism decided whose proposal and whose demand was to be considered. All negotiations finished after a proposal had been accepted. No group exhausted their pool in the negotiations. 3 Behavioral predictions Let us first consider standard prediction in the negotiation stage. Before knowing their type, subjects have the same bargaining power and therefore they can and will enforce to get get half of the pie. Thus, if the cake size equals c, a rational and selfish subjects accepts a proposal of least c/2-3. Therefore, this offer will be made. This implies that proposals and demands should not differ within and across the treatment groups. However, we expect that principles of distributive justice shape offers and minimum demands in specific ways within each treatment. Several experimental studies have shown how luck and merit influence distribution preferences and negotiation outcomes (see for example Hoffman et al. (1994), Burrows and Loomes (1994), Ruffle (1998), Konow (2003), or Durante and Putterman (2009)). These studies suggest that distributional norms differ between the luck and the skill treatment. Hence, we expect the following empirical results in our experiment. First, low (high) contributors make higher (lower) minimum demands in the luck treatment than in the skill treatment. Second, low (high) contributors propose less (more) generous distributions to the other group member in the luck treatment than in the skill treatment. These distributions 9 imply that, in the skill treatment, the correlation between proposals/demands and a subject�’s contributions to the common pool is significantly larger than in the luck treatment. The focus of our paper is on the education treatment. The egalitarian and the desert principles conflict in this treatment. The assignment of productivity-enhancing education occurs at random and supports the application of the egalitarian principle. However, each subject still has to produce and contribute to the common pool. Moreover, the size of the individual contribution of each group member depends also on her productivity relative to the performance of the fellow (un-)educated participants. Therefore, each individual has an impact on the size of the common pool. This impact provides a motive for the application of the desert principle. The experimental setup provides a clean environment for testing whether subjects consider a higher contribution via randomly assigned education as luck or as merit. We expect that demands and proposals in the education treatment are between those of the skill treatment and those of the luck treatment. It is an open question if the tendency is towards the former or the latter treatment. 4 Procedure and Results The experiment was conducted at the lakelab at the University of Konstanz. We programmed the experiment with z-Tree (Fischbacher, 2007) and recruited 190 participants among the students of the University using ORSEE (Greiner, 2004). All subjects received a show up-fee of 4 euros (about 5.75 US-dollars at the time of the experiment (Autumn 2009 and Spring 2010)) and additionally 0.15 euros per experimental point. In each treatment, all subjects received identical instructions, including comprehension questions. Once all subjects had answered the questions correctly, the conductor of the experiment summarized the experiment in a standardized text again. All instructions were framed in a neutral way, they are attached in the appendix. We conducted 12 sessions in total, eleven with 24 subjects per session. One session in the skill treatment included only 22 participants. Subjects earned on average 22.93 euros, including the show up fee. Table 2 shows the number of subjects and the average contribution of the high contributor in each treatment. A high contributor is a person who contributed 130 points or more to the common pool. Note that the number of subjects in the skill treatment is almost twice as large as in each of the other treatments. In this treatment, we consider only subjects in those groups as relevant in which one subject contributed 120 points or less and the other subject contributed 130 or more points. This provision ensures that the size of the common 10 pool is comparable across all treatments8. Therefore, we can denote the contribution in percentage points. The difference in mean contribution of high contributors between the skill and the education treatment is not significant (p = .323, according to the Wilcoxon rank sum test). Table 2: Number of subjects, common pool sizes and mean contribution of high contributors (in percentages) across the treatments Treatment Subjects Groups Common pool size Contribution of the high contributor* Mean St.Dev Mean St. Dev Skill All obs. 142 71 246.90 100.10 68.26% 12.35 Relevant** 72 36 254.44 43.52 72.35% 10.86 Education 72 36 250 60.62 75.48% 9.74 Luck 72 36 250 52.92 75.21% 11.11 *The high contributor are the subjects whose contribution was in the upper half within the session. **In the skill treatment, the relevant observations are the subjects in groups with one high and one low contributor. These groups are comparable with the other treatments. First we investigate whether treatments differ with respect to the minimum demands. Table 3 provides the minimum demands of high and low contributors and their proposed share for themselves in each treatment. 8 Hence, it is also not a problem that in one session only 22 subjects participated. The reduction in subjects just implies that the expected number of relevant observations is smaller in this session than in the other ones. 11 Table 3: Minimum demands and proposals of high and low contributors across the treatments Treatment Subjects Minimum demand of the high contributors Proposal of the high contributors for herself Mean St. Dev Mean St. Dev Skill 36 65.69% 9.66 67.56% 11.79 Education 36 61.42% 11.76 66.42% 11.09 Luck 36 59.39% 10.48 63.33% 11.21 Minimum demand of the low contributor Proposal of the low contributor Mean St. Dev Mean St. Dev Skill 36 34.5% 9.91 37.97% 10.80 Education 36 40.25% 10.57 41.69% 9.95 Luck 36 37.67% 10.25 42.47% 11.16 Minimum Demand: Minimum share of the common pool for the demanding subject. Proposal: Proposed share of the common pool for herself (i.e. not for the other group member). We find a significant difference in minimum demands between high contributors in the skill and in the luck treatment (Wilcoxon rank sum test, p = .010). The difference between the low contributors in those treatments is not significant (p = .107). The demands of low contributors in the skill and in the education treatment differ significantly (Wilcoxon rank sum test, p = .020). The proposals of the high contributors differ between the luck and the skill treatment (p = 0.069; according to the Wilcoxon rank-sum test). Low contributors in the skill treatment do not make significantly more generous proposals than those in the other treatments. The relationship between proposals (demands) and the contribution to the common pool provides more specific information about differences in distribution norms between the three treatments. We derive the role of individual contributions via OLS estimations of the proposed share for the other player (own minimum demand) in each treatment, with the own share of production as the single independent variable. Table 4 shows the relationship in the three treatments. Note that we subtract 50% from proposals, demands and production shares. Thus the constant term in the regression output shows how proposals and demands deviate from an equal sharing of the common pool. 12 Table 4: OLS estimations of first round proposals and demands in the different treatments (in %) Dependent Variable Proposed Share for herself (-50%) Minimum Demand (-50%) Skill Treatment Share of Production (-50%) .671 (.039)*** .680 (.035)*** Constant 2.764 (.973)*** .097 (.863) Adjusted R² .804 .843 Education Treatment Share of Production (-50%) .485 (.041)*** .418 (.045)*** Constant 4.056 (1.110)*** .833 (1.220) Adjusted R² .665 .548 Luck Treatment Share of Production (-50%) .408 (.045)*** .428 (.040)*** Constant 2.903 (1.224)** -1.472 (1.094) Adjusted R² .538 .618 *** significance level p<.01; ** p<.05; N = 72 in each OLS estimation, standard errors in parentheses The results confirm the existence of �“moral property rights�” (Gächter and Riedl, 2002), as they show a strong relationship between contributions and proposals (demands) even in the luck treatment. Most subjects accept that a randomly determined large contribution implies an entitlement to a rather high share of the common pool, even if the other player was luckier in her contribution. The production coefficients for proposals and demands are remarkably similar within each treatment. We then estimate if the impact of production shares on demands and proposals differs across the treatments. Here we exploit the interaction terms between the treatment variables (luck and skill) and a subject�’s share of production (see table 5). 13 Table 5: OLS estimations of first round proposals and demands across all treatments. (in %), Reference: Education Treatment Dependent Variable: Proposed Share for herself (-50%) Minimum Demand (-50%) Share of Production (-50%) .485 (.041)*** .418 (.039)*** Luck -1.153 (1.565) -2.306 (1.512) Luck Share of Production (-50%) -.077 (.057) .011 (.055) Skill -1.292 (1.565) -.736 (1.512) Skill Share of Production (-50%) .186 (.060)*** .262 (.058)*** Constant 4.056 (1.107)*** .833 (1.069) Adjusted R² .685 .691 *** significance level p<.01; N = 216 in each OLS estimation, standard errors in parentheses The interaction terms (Luck Share of Production and Merit Share of Production) indicate if the impact of production shares on demands and proposals differs significantly across the treatments. The results show that individual contributions are more relevant for proposals and demands in the skill treatment than in the other two treatments9. Distributional preferences in the education are remarkably similar to those in the luck treatment. This result implies that subjects consider only the random access to education but not the differences in performance within each educational group when they make their proposals and demands in the education treatment. Finally we focus on the adjusted R² for the OLS estimations in table 3. They are larger in the skill treatment than in the other two treatments. We calculated the residuals for each of these OLS estimations. An F-test reveals that the variance of these residuals in the skill treatment is much lower than in the other two treatments (The p-values for the differences in demand are all smaller than .01; for the differences in proposals they are smaller than .1). These differences indicate that there is a larger conflict of norms in the education and the luck treatment than in the skill treatment. Note however that actual acceptance rates of first round proposals were similar in the skill and in the luck treatment (52.8% and 55.6%, respectively) but significantly lower in the education treatment (37.5%, p = .067, in comparison with the skill treatment, and p = .030 in comparison with the luck treatment). Furthermore the actual 9 A more detailed analysis and the descriptive statistics in table 3 show that this difference in relevance of contributions between the skill and the other two treatments derives in particularly from differences among high contributors. The descriptive statistics in table 3 suggest the same. However, due to the limited number of observations, significant results of such a detailed analysis obtain only for differences in demands but not proposals. 14 number of bargaining rounds required to find an acceptable proposal did not differ across the treatments. About 75% of the groups find an agreement in round 1 or 2. Apparently, the anticipation of differences in bargaining behavior across the treatments affects behavior in the production period. The reader may recall that we standardized the contributions to the common pool in all treatments. In the skill as well as in the education treatment, the size of the contribution depended on the number of correctly answered questions. In the education treatment half of the subjects had learned 5% of the relevant questions, as did all subjects in the skill. Because of the random assignment into the different treatment groups and into the specific role, the earnings in the production period (i.e. the responses to the questions) should not differ for these subjects. However, this is not the case. Table 6 shows the average performance in the production period10 across the treatments. The difference between the skill treatment and the �“uneducated�” subjects in the production period is significant at the 10% level11. This difference suggests that subjects in the skill treatment have a stronger incentive to provide correct answers. One plausible explanation for this behavior is the expectation among subjects that individual performance is more relevant in the skill treatment than in the education treatment. Moral property rights provide another explanation. Uneducated subjects in the education treatment anticipate that they can contribute only up to 120 points. Participants in the skill treatment can contribute up to 240 points. Since the notion of moral property rights assigns higher shares to higher contributors they induce lower incentives for uneducated subjects in the education treatment. 10 The difference between correct and wrong answers. 11 p = .095 (Wilcoxon rank-sum test). For the relevant observations, the p-value is .046. 15 Table 6: Number of subjects, share of learned answers and performance in the production period across the treatments Treatment Subjects Share of learned answers Performance in the production period St.Dev Skill All obs. 142 5% 12.11 8.06 Relevant obs. 72 5% 13.01 7.78 Education 36 5% 9.81 10.50 36 95% 55.94 3.47 Luck 72 50% 36.06 4.67 The difference between correct and wrong answers determines the performance in the production period. 5 Summary and Conclusion In this paper, we investigate how people respond to one of the most important sources of inequality, unequal access to education. In a real-effort experiment, subjects provide an effort, which determines their contribution to a common pool. In the subsequent negotiation stage, we assess how people distribute the contribution. Depending on the treatment, luck, skill or random access to skill-enhancing education determined the size of the individual contributions. Our subjects received clear information about these determinants of contribution. Due to the experimental design, the size of individual contributions and the common pool did not vary systematically across the treatments. Therefore, we could eliminate crucial confounds that restrict the analysis of inequalities of opportunities in previous survey and experimental studies. In all treatments, proposals and demands are correlated with individual contributions to the common pool, even if luck rather than innate or acquired skills determine the size of these contributions. Individual contributions matter more when innate skill rather than luck determines outcomes. Random access to skill-enhancing education turns out to be perceived similarly as the luck situation. Subjects without access to such education make similar demands and proposals as those subjects with a randomly determined contribution. This similarity reveals that when the inequality in educational opportunities is salient, meritocratic criteria get out of focus. Our results show that redistribution of outputs that are produced by 16 saliently unequal opportunities is similar to redistribution after output created by luck alone. Unequal opportunities increase redistribution and, therefore, reduce the incentives to provide high output. Thus, public investments in education are less effective if there is not equal access to education. This implies that improved access to education can reduce inequality and increase social welfare. References Alesina, A. and Angeletos, G. M. "Fairness and Redistribution." The American Economic Review, 2005, 95(4), pp. 960-80. Alesina, A. and Glaeser, E. L. Fighting Poverty in the US and Europe: A World of Difference. Oxford University Press, USA, 2005. Alesina, A. and La Ferrara, E. "Preferences for Redistribution in the Land of Opportunities." Journal of Public Economics, 2005, 89(5-6), pp. 897-931. Benabou, R. and Tirole, J. "Belief in a Just World and Redistributive Politics." Quarterly Journal of Economics, 2006, 121(2), pp. 699-746. Bovenberg, A. L. and Jacobs, B. "Redistribution and Education Subsidies Are Siamese Twins." Journal of Public Economics, 2005, 89(11-12). Burrows, P. and Loomes, G. "The Impact of Fairness on Bargaining." Empirical Economics, 1994, 19(2), pp. 201-21. Cappelen, A. W.; Hole, A. D.; Sørensen, EØ and Tungodden, B. "The Pluralism of Fairness Ideals: An Experimental Approach." The American Economic Review, 2007, 97(3), pp. 818-27. Durante, R. and Putterman, L. "Preferences for Redistribution and Perception of Fairness: An Experimental Study." Working Papers, 2009. Fehr, E. and Schmidt, K. M. "A Theory of Fairness, Competition, and Cooperation*." Quarterly Journal of Economics, 1999, 114(3), pp. 817-68. Greiner, B. "The Online Recruitment System Orsee 2.0�–a Guide for the Organization of Experiments in Economics." Papers on Strategic Interaction, University of Cologne, Working Paper Series in Economics, 2004, 10. Grossman, M. "Education and Nonmarket Outcomes," E. Hanushek and F. Welch, Handbook of the Economics of Education. Amsterdam: Elsevier Science, 2006, 577-633. Hayek, F. A. "The Constitution of Liberty," Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1960. Hoffman, E.; McCabe, K.; Shachat, K. and Smith, V. "Preferences, Property Rights, and Anonymity in Bargaining Games." Games and Economic Behavior, 1994, 7(3), pp. 346-80. Konow, J. "Fair Shares: Accountability and Cognitive Dissonance in Allocation Decisions." American Economic Review, 2000, 90(4), pp. 1072-91. ____. "A Positive Theory of Economic Fairness." Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 1996, 31(1), pp. 13-35. ____. "Which Is the Fairest One of All? A Positive Analysis of Justice Theories." Journal of Economic Literature, 2003, 41(4), pp. 1188-239. Lamont, Julian and Favor, Christi. 2007. "Distributive Justice," Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/justice-distributive/. retrieved on 2009, Nov 26th Piketty, T. "Social Mobility and Redistributive Politics." The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 1995, pp. 551-84. Psacharopoulos, G. and Patrinos, H. A. "Returns to Investment in Education: A Further Update." Education Economics, 2004, 12(2), pp. 111-34. 17 Ruffle, B. J. "More Is Better, but Fair Is Fair: Tipping in Dictator and Ultimatum Games." Games and Economic Behavior, 1998, 23(2), pp. 247-65. Appendix A General Instructions for all participants (translated from German) Welcome to this economic experiment. If you read the following instructions carefully you will receive money in addition to the 4 euro show-up fee. Your earnings depend on your decisions and the decisions of other participants. Hence, please read the instructions carefully. If you have any questions please contact us before the actual experiment starts. During the experiment, it is forbidden to talk with the other participants. We will exclude you from this experiment and any payment if you violate this rule. During the experiment we use points instead of euros. We calculate all your earnings in points and exchange them into Euros at the end of the experiment. The exchange rate is 1 point = 0,15 euro At the end of the experiment, we will pay you all your points and the show-up fee of 4 euros in cash. Now we will explain the precise procedure of the experiment. Summary In this experiment you are a member in a group of 2 persons. The experiment has three phases. First comes a learning phase in which you can acquire knowledge. In the following production phase both members of the group can earn points by using their knowledge. Skill Treatment Education Treatment Luck Treatment Each person gets 10% of his produced points into a private account. Each person earns additional rank points which depend on the production of this person in comparison with all other participants. The group members differ with respect to the benefit they receive from the learning period. A die determines how much each member benefits. Each person gets 10% of his produced points in a private account. Each person earns additional rank points which depend on the production of this person in comparison with all other participants. The remaining points will be substituted by points that you draw from an urn and which you have to pay into a group account. There is an urn with high point scores and an urn with low ones. A die decides from which urn you can draw. Each person has to pay these rank points into a group account. In the third phase, the bargaining phase, the two group members negotiate about the distribution of this group account. Learning phase 18 In the learning phase you can prepare for the production phase. In the production phase your earnings increase in the number of correctly answered knowledge questions. In the learning phase you can learn some of these correct answers. We derived the questions from the game �“trivial pursuit�” and transformed them into multiple choice questions with four possible answers. You can also choose the option �“I do not know�”. We chose the questions randomly; they cover all areas of knowledge. In the learning phase, you can learn 60 questions and their corresponding correct answers. The screen is structured as follows: There are 6 pages with 10 questions each on your screen. You can go from one page to another as you wish. The red buttons show you the correct answer for a specific question. In the top right corner you can see the remaining time. You have 15 minutes time (900 sec.). Note that the questions in the production phase show up in a random sequence. You may not take notes, if you do we will exclude you from the experiment. After 15 minutes you will move automatically into the production phase. Lottery (only in the education treatment) At the beginning of the production phase, a die determines which group member benefits more strongly from the learning period. In each group, one member has learned 95% of the correct answers, the other member learns only 5% of them. 19 A randomly chosen person in this room will throw a six sided die and type into her computer whether the number is odd or even. You will see on your screen how many answers you will learn with an odd number and how many with an even one. Production phase The production phase lasts 15 minutes. You can earn points by answering 60 knowledge points correctly during this time. Skill Treatment Education Treatment Luck Treatment You have learned 5% of these questions. The die has determined whether you have learned 5% or 95% of these questions. You have learned 50% of these questions. The sequence of the questions is randomly determined. For a correct answer, you earn 2 points. For an incorrect answer, you lose 2 points. The option �“I do not know�” does not influence your score. You give your answer on a screen like this: On the top you see the number of answered questions. In the middle you see the question. Below the questions you find buttons for the 4 provided answers and the option �“I do not know�”. In the top right corner you can see the remaining time. 20 Private account and group account (in the skill and education treatments) At the end of the 15 minutes the computer calculates how many points are in your private account and how many go into your group account. 10% of the produced points go into your private income. If your score is negative, we deduct the 10% from your show-up fee. We substitute the remaining points with rank points, which depend on your score and the score of the other participants. The computer ranks the participants according to the number of points they have produced. Note that we rank all subjects (added in the education treatment: independent of the number of questions they have learned in the learning phase). The person with the lowest number of points receives 10 rank points, the person with the second lowest number 20 points, the person the third lowest number 30 points and so on. The person with the highest number will receive 240 points, if 24 persons are in the lab. If 2 or more persons have the same number of points, the computer assigns the rank points randomly. These assigned rank points go into the group account. Information about the received rank points: 21 If your point score is negative this has an impact on your private account but not on your group account. You will contribute at least 10 rank points to your group account. Example 1: You have answered 45 questions correctly and 5 incorrectly. You earned 80 points. The other group member has 35 correct answers and 10 wrong ones. She earned 50 points. In comparison with the other participants you have earned the seventh lowest number of points, the other member the third lowest number. Your private income: 10% of 80 = 8 points Private income of the other member:10% of 50 = 5 points Your income in rank points the seventh lowest point score: = 70 rank points The income of the other member in rank points the third lowest point score: = 30 rank points Your group’s account: 70 rank points + 30 rank points = 100 points Example 2: You have answered 15 questions correctly and 20 incorrectly. You earned -10 points. The other group member has 35 correct answers and 0 wrong ones. She earned 70 points. In comparison with the other participants you have earned the lowest number of points, the other member the eighth lowest number. 22 Your private income: 10% of -10 = -1 point Private income of the other member:10% of 70 = 7 points Your income in rank points the lowest point score: = 10 rank points The income of the other member in rank points the eigth lowest point score: = 80 rank points Your group’s account: 10 rank points + 80 rank points = 90 points This calculation is identical for all subjects. You will see it on your screen. You will receive information about your private account and how much each group member has contributed to the group account (in rank points as well as in shares (%)). You keep your private earnings. You will bargain with the other group member about the distribution of the group account in the next phase. Private account and group account (in the Luck treatment) At the end of the 15 minutes the computer calculates how many points are in your private account and how many go into your group account. 10% of the produced points go into your private income. If your score is negative, we deduct the 10% from your show-up fee. We substitute the remaining points with points you have drawn from an urn. Points from the Urn and the group account Your draw from the urn depends on the urn you draw from. There are two different urns. In the LOW urn you can draw between 10 and 120 points. In the HIGH urn, you can draw between 130 and 240 points. A die decides from which urn you may draw. A randomly chosen person in the lab throws a six-sided die and types into his computer whether the resulting number is odd or even. Your screen shows you from which urn you may draw in case of an odd number and from which in case of an even one. In each group of two persons, one person can draw from the high urn and one from the low urn. The conductors of the experiment will go around with the urn and you can make your draw. You will type the drawn number of points into the following screen. These points substitute your remaining points from the production phase. 23 In the first line is the number of points you collected in the production phase. Below you see the number of points in your private account and the number of points which will be substituted with points from the urn. The points from the urn go into a group account. Since the potential draws are distributed between 10 and 240 points, you contribute at least 10 points into the group account. Example 1: You have answered 45 questions correctly and 5 incorrectly. You earned 80 points. The other group member has 35 correct answers and 10 wrong ones. She earned 50 points. Your private income: 10% of 80 = 8 points Private income of the other member:10% of 50 = 5 points You were able to draw from the high urn and drew 150 points. The other group member had to draw from the low urn and drew 20 points. These points substitute the remaining points from the production phase. Your group’s account: 150 urn points + 20 urn points = 170 points This calculation is identical for all subjects. You will see it on your screen. You receive information about your private account and how much each group member has contributed to the group account (in rank points as well as in shares (%)). You keep your private earnings. You bargain with the other group member about the distribution of the group account in the next phase. Bargaining Phase In the bargaining phase both group members bargain about the distribution of the points in the group account. Negotiations proceed as follows. There exists a role A and a role B. The group member with role A proposes a distribution of the points in the group account. The member with role B makes a claim for a minimum share of the group account that she wants to 24 receive. If the proposed share of A for B is equal to or exceeds the minimum share demanded by B, the proposal of A is accepted and the negotiation ends. Negotiation fails if the proposed share is smaller than the minimum demand. In this case, 6 points are withdrawn from the group account and a new bargaining round starts. The bargaining phase can go on for several rounds until an agreement or until the group account is empty. In each round, roles A and B are assigned randomly to the group members. Detailed Procedure of a Bargaining Round 1. Decision as A: First both group members make a proposal about the distribution of the group account by stating a share (in percentages) for themselves and a share for the other group member. 2. Decision as B: In this second step, both group members state the minimum share of the group account they want to receive. 3. Afterwards, a lottery decides which member has role A and which member has role B. 4. The computer compares the proposal of A with the minimum demand of B: a. An agreement is reached if the proposal of A is equal to or larger than B�’s minimum demand. In this case the points in the group account are distributed according to A�’s proposal. b. There is no agreement if A�’s proposal is smaller than B�’s minimum demand. In this case the group account is reduced by 6 points and a new bargaining round starts. 5. In the next bargaining round both group members make a proposal for the distribution of the group account and a minimum demand. 6. Again, a lottery decides the assignment of roles A and B. 7. The computer compares the proposal of A with the minimum demand of B: The experiment ends once the group members reach an agreement or the group account is empty. In the latter case, no one receives a payment from the group account. Example 1: There are 100 points on the group account – 70 from you and 30 from the other group member. Both group members bargain about the distribution of this group account by making a proposal and a minimum demand. Your distribution proposal (for role A): 80% for you and 20% for the other group member Your minimum demand (for role B): at least 70% for you The distribution proposal of the other member(for role A): 40% for herself and 60% for you. Her minimum demand (for role B): at least 40% for herself A lottery decides that you are in role A and the other group member in role B. A comparison between your proposal and the minimum demand of the other group member shows that there is no agreement in this bargaining round. You proposed 20% to the other member, but she demanded at least 40%. Example 2: There are, again, 100 points on the group account – 70 from you and 30 from the other group member. Both group members bargain about the distribution of this group account by making a proposal and a minimum demand. 25 Your distribution proposal (for role A): 60% for you and 40% for the other group member Your minimum demand (for role B): at least 60% for you The distribution proposal of the other member(for role A): 40% for herself and 60% for you. Her minimum demand (for role B B): at least 35% for herself A lottery decides that you are in role A and the other group member in role B. A comparison between your proposal and the minimum demand of the other group member shows that there is an agreement in this bargaining round. You proposed 40% to the other member, and she demanded at least 35%. The bargaining procedure on your screen. You type your proposal in the following screen. In the top left corner you see the contribution of each group member into the group account (in points). In the top right corner you see the current number of points in the group account and the current bargaining round. Below this information, you can make your proposal for role A. 26 You will type your minimum demand in the following screen. In the top left corner is the contribution of each group member into the group account (in points). In the top right corner is the current number of points in the group account and the current bargaining round. Below this information, you can make your minimum demand for role B. A lottery decides which member has role A and which member has role B. The computer compares the proposal of A with the minimum demand of B: The bargaining ends once the group members reach an agreement or the group account is empty. At the end of the bargaining, you can see your income and the experiment ends. 27 Training Questions (From the education treatment: we adapted the questions for the other treatments) Please answer the following questions. They do not affect your final payment. Please signal if you have questions or once you have completed the answers. 1) In the production phase, you knew 95% of the questions from the learning phase. You have answered 45 questions correctly and 10 incorrectly. The other group member knew 5% of the questions and has answered 20 questions correctly and 25 incorrectly. a. How many points are in your private account? ________________________ b. How many points are in the private account of the other group member? ______________ 2) You earned 60 points in the production period, the other group member 40. In comparison with the other participants, you have the fifth lowest score and the other member the second lowest. a. How many rank points do you get? __________________ b. How many rank points does the other group member get? ________ c. How many points are in the group account? __________________ 3) After the production phase, your group has 100 points in its account. You propose a share of 80% for yourself and 20% for the other group member and the lottery assigns role A to you. The other group member demands at least 10% for herself. a. Is there an agreement? __________________________________ b. If yes, how many points will you get? _______ c. If yes, how many points will the other group member get? _______ 4) At the beginning of the third bargaining round, there are 138 points on your group account. You have been assigned to role A and you proposed 50% of the group account for yourself and 50% for the other group member. This member demanded (in role B) at least 60% for herself. Therefore, bargaining fails and a new bargaining round starts. a. How many points are on the group account at the beginning of the fourth bargaining round? _____________________ Learning and Peer Effects Gerald Eisenkopf Research Paper Series Thurgau Institute of Economics No. 21 september 2007 Text2: Konstanzer Online-Publikations-System (KOPS) URN: http://nbn-resolving.de/urn:nbn:de:bsz:352-opus-124339 URL: http://kops.ub.uni-konstanz.de/volltexte/2010/12433/ work_4krgqgyxoffsfose3aa2dquvpm ---- Shinner.qxd Justice & Racial Conciliation: Two Visions The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Shelby, Tommie. 2011. “Justice & Racial Conciliation: Two Visions.” Daedalus 140 (1) (January): 95–107. doi:10.1162/daed_a_00062. Published Version 10.1162/daed_a_00062 Citable link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:34253788 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Other Posted Material, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use#LAA http://osc.hul.harvard.edu/dash/open-access-feedback?handle=&title=Justice%20&%20Racial%20Conciliation:%20Two%20Visions&community=1/1&collection=1/2&owningCollection1/2&harvardAuthors=2a066245c72b7141f10068d1e6714474&departmentAfrican%20and%20African%20American%20Studies http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:34253788 http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of-use#LAA http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of-use#LAA http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of-use#LAA Justice & Racial Conciliation: Two Visions Tommie Shelby © 2011 by the American Academy of Arts & Sciences TOMMIESHELBY is Professor of African and African American Studies and Professor of Philos- ophy at Harvard University. His recent publications include We Who Are Dark: The Philosophical Foundations of Black Solidarity (2005) and “Justice, Deviance, and the Dark Ghetto,” Philosophy & Public Affairs (2007). He is also the coeditor of the magazine Transition. Many Americans, from all racial backgrounds, are rightly proud that their nation has elected its ½rst black president.1 In a society long weary of its race problem, such a momentous event has led some to assert that we have, de½nitively, realized Martin Luther King, Jr.’s dream. King, though still reviled in some quarters, is widely regarded as one of the founders of our new post-segrega- tion republic. His interpretation of the American dream is a touchstone for measuring racial prog- ress in the post–civil rights era. It is therefore an appropriate time to revisit Dr. King’s vision for race relations in U.S. society. Indeed, Obama is frequently compared to King. Some of the comparisons flatter the president; others do not. However, I will not weigh side by side the personal character or practical achieve- ments of the two men. Clearly, both leaders are highly educated and charismatic; both have a gift for oratory and the ability to inspire; and both have made indelible marks on U.S. history. But because of differences in their respective voca- tions–mass movement leader and minister, on the one hand; Democratic Party politician and elected of½cial, on the other–and because Obama is operating within a very different historical con- text than did King, any such comparison is likely to be misleading and unfair. Yet we can reflect on, and learn from, these ½gures’ respective visions for American race relations. With this purpose in mind, I focus on ideas, on the philosophy that Dædalus Winter 2011 95 should underpin political practice. My primary concern is the mounting influ- ence of a particular vision of race in the United States, one that I believe deserves more skepticism, or at least much less enthusiasm, than it is currently receiving. Any vision for race relations in Ameri- ca should ½rst be rooted in an honest and historically informed assessment of exist- ing racial realities. Second, it should out- line basic ideals, the intermediate and ul- timate goals for which we ought to strive. Finally, the vision should specify the means by which we are to realize its stat- ed ideals given prevailing racial realities. I am not interested in utopian fantasies but in realistic ideas. Though they often speak of their “dreams” and “hopes,” King and Obama are both practical think- ers. Their writings and speeches on race explain where we are (including how we got here), where we should be going, and how we can get there. Their visions have much in common. But Obama’s vision, politically shrewd and pragmatic though it may be, is marred by its defective mor- al content. Comparing his vision with King’s reveals this de½ciency. In his famous “I Have a Dream” speech (1963), King described the racial realities of his day.2 He emphasized that although slavery in the United States had ended one hundred years before, black Ameri- cans were still not free. Life chances for blacks were severely diminished, “crip- pled” by racial segregation and wide- spread discrimination. Blacks were most- ly poor despite living in a society with tremendous wealth. A great many were socially marginalized and isolated in slums. Blacks did not have equal citizen- ship because they were denied the rights to vote and hold public of½ce. They were victims of police brutality and vicious acts of domestic terrorism. Under con- stant assault by racist ideology, blacks struggled to maintain self-respect and self-esteem. The Civil Rights Act (1964) and the Voting Rights Act (1965) helped to break through the legal barriers to black inclu- sion in American social life, to curb dis- crimination, and to empower blacks po- litically. King thus proclaimed in Where Do We Go from Here? (1967) that many whites had come to accept racial equali- ty, at least in principle, and to reject de jure segregation and discrimination. Nev- ertheless, troubling racial disparities–in income, education, wealth, employment, health, and poverty–caused by continu- ing discrimination and centuries of gross mistreatment and abuse, remained un- addressed. He argued that racist opposi- tion was not the only reason these dis- parities had yet to be met with an ade- quate response. An equally if not more dif½cult obstacle was that most whites, even many who rejected racism, resisted racial justice measures that might have a personal cost. As King wrote, “The great majority of Americans . . . are uneasy with injustice but unwilling yet to pay a signif- icant price to eradicate it.”3 In response to this resistance, King reminded us that meaningful attempts to bring about a just society have unavoidable costs. Quality education for all children, decent and well-paying jobs for adults, and the erad- ication of slums for the bene½t of the poor require great resources. King was committed to the fundamen- tal ideals of racial equality and integra- tion. He understood the former as a de- mand of social justice that could be de- scribed in terms of two principles. First, each citizen, regardless of his or her race, should enjoy equal civic standing and the equal protection of the law. Justice does not permit second-class citizenship on the basis of race. Second, government should ensure that no one’s basic rights are curtailed or general life prospects 96 Dædalus Winter 2011 Justice & Racial Conciliation reduced because of the racial prejudice of others. It is not enough that the state refrain from treating some citizens as if they were civic inferiors unworthy of equal concern and respect. Private indi- viduals and associations must be made to follow suit, at least when individuals’ basic liberties or vital socioeconomic opportunities are at issue. Moving toward racial equality required a concrete policy of desegregation. The primary goal of desegregation was to abolish the unfair exclusions and prohi- bitions of Jim Crow, a social system that gave whites privileges and advantages they did not merit, deprived blacks of rights and opportunities they deserved, and generally stigmatized black people as inferior. To end discrimination in housing, education, employment, and lending, nondiscrimination laws needed to be enacted and scrupulously enforced. In the political sphere, achieving racial equality meant granting blacks the un- fettered right to vote and hold political of½ce. The civil rights movement, through lit- igation and persistent pressure on Con- gress and several presidents, abolished a hideous and terrifying race-based regime. Previously, the subordination of blacks was the law of the land in the South, and discrimination against blacks was wide- spread throughout the country. Many, then and now, see this tremendous vic- tory as the end of the struggle for racial equality. King did not share this view. He recognized that the many decades of slavery and Jim Crow had severely disad- vantaged blacks (especially in education, employment, wealth, and housing) and had injured their self-respect and psycho- logical well-being. Even if the new civil rights laws were impartially and effective- ly enforced, the damage inflicted by the long reign of white supremacy would remain. Repairing it was an urgent issue of racial justice. Certainly, in a market society, where competition determines most people’s life prospects, “the pursuit of happiness” as an equal right of all citi- zens would not be guaranteed until blacks were no longer handicapped by the lega- cy of white domination. According to King, justice, in its most basic sense, means giving persons what they are due. Ful½lling this demand often means treating everyone the same. But sometimes it calls for treating people differently. This point has particular rele- vance with regard to serious injustices, whereby a certain class of persons has suffered mistreatment and is disadvan- taged as a result. As King says in Why We Can’t Wait (1963), “[O]ur society has been doing something special against the Negro for hundreds of years. How then can he be absorbed into the mainstream of American life if we do not do some- thing special for him now, in order to balance the equation and equip him to compete on a just and equal basis?”4 Many people–perhaps relying on the familiar line about being judged by the content of one’s character rather than by one’s skin color–wrongly believe that King rejected reparations and all other race-targeted, compensatory mea- sures for black Americans. In fact, he supported such recompense: Few people consider the fact that, in addition to being enslaved for two cen- turies, the Negro was, during all those years, robbed of the wages of his toil. No amount of gold could provide an adequate compensation for the exploi- tation and humiliation of the Negro in America down through the centuries. Not all the wealth of this affluent soci- ety could meet the bill. Yet a price can be placed on unpaid wages. The ancient common law has always provided a rem- edy for the appropriation of the labor of Dædalus Winter 2011 97 Tommie Shelby one human being by another. This law should be made to apply for American Negroes. The payment should be in the form of a massive program by the gov- ernment of special, compensatory mea- sures which could be regarded as a set- tlement in accordance with the accept- ed practice of common law.5 In addition to the ideal of racial equal- ity, King advocated integration. From a political perspective, integration is linked to the requirements of justice. Certainly, blacks and other racial minorities should not be formally excluded from participat- ing in the social, economic, and political life of the nation. But these previously excluded groups should also be actively included as equal and indispensable participants. Such inclusion should not amount to tokenism, in which a small non-white elite is created, integrated, and made to represent symbolically the “progress” of their respective groups, leaving most in those factions still social- ly marginalized and politically power- less. Justice requires that whites fully share power and decision-making with non-whites, erasing all signs of white domination. The members of different racial groups must ultimately recognize their mutual dependence and equal sta- tus; they must solve their problems to- gether. Integration, in this sense, is the realization of the republican ideal of collective self-determination in a multi- racial society. King was also intensely concerned with the ethical side of integration. In “The Ethical Demands for Integration” (1962), he explained that our goal should not be mere desegregation and nondiscrimina- tion.6 Rather, we must aim to build a so- ciety in which the members of different races have a sense of goodwill toward one another and think of themselves as col- lectively constituting one people. We should not be content with interracial détente; we should strive for interracial civic friendship–that is, fraternity in a multiracial society of equals. This unity should be founded on mutual respect and understanding. King evokes the ethi- cal dimension of integration in his mem- orable line, “I have a dream that one day on the hills of Georgia, sons of former slaves and sons of former slave-owners will be able to sit down together at the table of brotherhood.”7 The goal of mere desegregation is de- ½cient in part because it suggests that we should be satis½ed if nondiscrimina- tion laws are obeyed out of prudence (to avoid legal sanctions, for example) or out of general respect for the law. For King, it was crucial that we obey these laws not simply because we fear punish- ment or recognize the authority of law, but because such laws are morally right: because they embody the worthy ideal of integration. Racial equality and political integration, King insisted, were pressing matters of justice and thus enforceable through law. On the other hand, he did not believe that the ethical ideal of interracial unity could be enforced. Implementing legisla- tion, along with its steadfast enforcement, is de½nitely essential to regulating the behavior of those who refuse to respect the demands of justice. Furthermore, a racially just polity is a necessary con- dition for genuine interracial fraterni- ty. However, trust, respect, and mutual concern cannot be achieved through law enforcement. A complete resolution of the race problem in America therefore requires that each individual willingly commits to integration. To achieve his stated ends, King sup- ported militant mass protest. He believed in uncompromising dissent from and active agitation against racial injustice. This resistance should take the form of 98 Dædalus Winter 2011 Justice & Racial Conciliation organized boycotts, civil disobedience, and public demonstrations. These tactics sought to highlight egregious wrongs and expose hypocrisy, to awaken and motivate the morally complacent majority, and to put economic and political pressure on those with the power to change condi- tions. King is part of a long and venera- ble tradition of freedom ½ghters who fervently believe that injustices are never corrected without the determination and hard work of individuals openly ½ghting together for what is right. King held central the precept that in the struggle to achieve racial equality and in- tegration, we must use means that are as pure as the ends we seek. The principle “by any means necessary” was not to his mind a morally permissible stance, even for a severely oppressed people. More- over, he was convinced that morally sus- pect measures could never realize our ideals; the ethical means available were suf½cient. King further cautioned against destroying our chances of reaching our ultimate goals by using means designed to secure short-term or intermediate ends. For these reasons, King believed that the ½ght for racial justice and integration must be nonviolent. He frequently ad- monished blacks to reject political vio- lence and not to succumb to hatred and blanket mistrust of whites. To be sure, violent resistance would be ineffective: blacks lacked the resources and tactical means to win a confrontation with white racists; black aggression would give white supremacists an excuse to slaughter blacks not in the movement, thus undermining black communal support; and violence would alienate needed white allies and obscure the moral issues the struggle meant to highlight. King also objected to political violence on moral principle. Such tactics were simply wrong, regard- less of whether they could secure con- cessions from those in power. Even if political violence could achieve some intermediate goals–such as curbing po- lice brutality and discouraging white ter- rorism–it would undermine the ultimate goal of interracial fraternity. King also rejected black separatism, not only as an ideal but as a means to black liberation. Undertaking the struggle for racial equality and integration demand- ed interracial cooperation. Beyond the pragmatic point that blacks could not succeed alone, King objected to racial separatism on moral grounds. Not all whites are untrustworthy or malicious, he contended, and blacks should not treat them as if they were. To reject white par- ticipants in the movement would dishon- or those whites who made great sacri½ces –including the ultimate sacri½ce–in the pursuit of racial justice. Moreover, inter- racial fraternity will arrive only after the various racial groups in America recog- nize that they have a “common destiny”: to live together as one people. Such mu- tual understanding and respect between the races can come about only through frequent contact and cooperation. In Where Do We Go from Here? King makes this point forcefully and eloquently: “Since we [black people] are Americans the solution to our problem will not come through seeking to build a separate black nation within a nation, but by ½nding that creative minority of the concerned from the oft-times apathetic majority, and together moving toward that color- less power that we all need for security and justice.”8 In his books and speeches (especially those focused on race), Obama frequently invokes, explicitly and implicitly, King’s dream for America.9 He endorses King’s ideals of racial equality and integration, regarding an end to discrimination and prejudice, the elimination of racial dis- parities, and interracial unity as ultimate Dædalus Winter 2011 99 Tommie Shelby goals. Though many of his supporters– and detractors, for that matter–view his ascent to the presidency as con½rmation that the bounced check King lamented has ½nally been cashed, and that we now live in a “post-racial” society, Obama has consistently cautioned against this inter- pretation of current racial realities. In The Audacity of Hope (2006), for example, he writes, “[T]o say that we are one peo- ple is not to suggest that race no longer matters–that the ½ght for equality has been won, or that the problems that mi- norities face in this country today are largely self-inflicted.”10 In “A More Perfect Union” (2008), the famous speech Obama delivered in Phil- adelphia (“the city of brotherly love”), he forthrightly stated that, while we have made undeniable progress, the problem of race has not been solved.11 Existing racial disparities–in education, wealth, and income–are, he claims, in part the debilitating consequences of slavery and Jim Crow. Pervasive discrimination in the past–in housing, employment, and lending–explains the current racial dis- parities in wealth and income. The fact that blacks were prevented from amass- ing assets they might pass on to their children largely accounts for urban and rural poverty. As he observed in his re- marks at the 2009 naacp Centennial Convention, the highest barriers to ra- cial equality today are the structural in- equalities that are the legacy of racial injustice in the United States.12 Indeed, while Obama often empha- sizes how the injustices of the past still shape our present, he also highlights current racial injustices. In The Audacity of Hope, he explains how degrading ra- cial stereotypes and unconscious bias lead to discrimination in employment and law enforcement. In his controver- sial statements about the arrest of Pro- fessor Henry Louis Gates, Jr.–remarks that, in his haste to quell the controver- sy, he did not retract–Obama made it clear that he believes racial pro½ling of blacks and Latinos remains a serious problem. He has publicly registered his opposition to a recent immigration law, passed in Arizona in April 2010, on the grounds that it will invite racial pro½l- ing and harassment of Latinos. In his Philadelphia speech on race, he called the racial achievement gap a result of the segregated and inferior public schools that serve minorities. Black families are often weak or broken not just because of irresponsible fathers, but because black men have been denied equal economic opportunity. He claimed that a lack of basic public services in poor black neigh- borhoods (effective law enforcement, parks, regular garbage pick-up, and building-code enforcement, for exam- ple) has fostered urban violence and blight. Though some blacks, he noted, have heroically triumphed over many obstacles to succeed (sometimes aided by af½rmative action policies), others have been unable to defeat these unfair odds. Instead, they often dwell in our deteriorated urban centers or languish in our prisons without hope or prospects. What is to be done? As Obama said on the one hundredth anniversary of the establishment of the oldest civil rights organization in America, “[T]he ½rst thing we need to do is make real the words of the naacp charter and eradicate prej- udice, bigotry, and discrimination among citizens of the United States.” He has also consistently made clear the need to vig- orously enforce nondiscrimination and civil rights laws. In other words, a per- son’s ability to acquire a stable and well- paying job, decent and affordable hous- ing, credit at fair interest rates, or quality education should not be hampered by the racial prejudice and bias of others. Moreover, it is the responsibility of gov- 100 Dædalus Winter 2011 Justice & Racial Conciliation ernment to ensure that this principle is realized; market forces are not suf½cient. Obama also believes that we must guar- antee fairness and impartiality in our criminal justice system. Due process is a basic civil right, and racism, whether conscious or not, must not be allowed to abridge this fundamental liberty. How are we to respond to the racial disparities and inherited disadvantages caused by historical injustices? Obama does not support reparations for the descendants of slaves or the victims of the segregation regime, though he con- cedes that af½rmative action in higher education can be a useful, if limited, tool to expand opportunity for under- represented racial minorities. Instead, he favors universal programs that aim to help all who are disadvantaged, regard- less of race, over policies that aim to compensate or aid speci½c racial groups. Because racial minorities are dispropor- tionately disadvantaged, he reasons, they will reap a large share of the bene½ts of such policies. In The Audacity of Hope, Obama offers two reasons to explain why an emphasis on universal programs over race-speci½c ones makes good political sense. The ½rst is that white guilt has run out. White Americans now resent blacks’ continu- ing grievances and sense of victimhood. Thus, they do not support policies that grant the legitimacy of black claims of injustice. Second, whites perceive that spending our limited public resources on further attempts to create racial equality or end ghetto poverty runs contrary to their self-interest. Such efforts not only mean higher taxes; they mean fewer pub- lic resources to aid whites. Obama con- cludes that policies to help all in need– which would, in theory, disproportion- ately aid racial minorities–should be favored in the current context. He be- lieves universal policies will more likely garner multiracial support, including white support. Like King, Obama is convinced that we cannot establish a just society without interracial cooper- ation. Thus, we must chart a course to bridge the racial divide and foster ra- cial conciliation. But there are further obstacles to the realization of this vision, and Obama is keenly aware of them. In “A More Per- fect Union,” he explained that as a result of our history of racism and the pain it has caused, many blacks remain angry– at times, bitter. Though sometimes jus- ti½ed, anger can be counterproductive. Not only can it blind blacks to their re- sponsibility to improve their own con- dition, but it can prevent the formation of interracial alliances essential for real social change. Obama noted that some working- and middle-class whites are angry, too. They do not believe they are privileged by their race; they believe they have earned everything they have. They were not the ones who committed the injustices against blacks and thus feel no obligation to correct historical wrongs. Besides, they face serious economic chal- lenges of their own, challenges that threat- en their hopes and dreams. They resent when desegregation efforts mean their children are bused to schools outside their neighborhoods; when af½rmative action allows racial minorities to gain ad- vantages in employment and education; and when they are accused of racism for expressing fears about black crime. As with black anger, Obama insists that white resentment toward racial minori- ties is often counterproductive. It dis- tracts, he said, from the “real culprits” behind the economic insecurity that all working- and middle-class people expe- rience: namely, a corporate culture of greed, a government that answers to cor- porate interests but is unresponsive to the needs of ordinary citizens, and eco- Dædalus Winter 2011 101 Tommie Shelby nomic policies that favor the wealthy. At times, Obama seems committed to an underlying social theory that considers it counterproductive to challenge whites directly for clinging to racist ideologies. These ideologies, so the theory goes, are ultimately rooted in a widespread sense of economic insecurity and political pow- erlessness among whites. It is better to attack the roots of the problem–corpo- rate dominance over our lives and our democracy–without condemning whites for harboring racist attitudes and accept- ing racial stereotypes. If, through inter- racial cooperation and collective resolve, we ½x these underlying problems, then this kind of racism should, more or less, take care of itself. In the meantime, we shore up enforcement of nondiscrimina- tion laws so that blacks and Latinos are protected from the most serious conse- quences of white racism. Obama thinks we can, or at least should, set aside old racial divisions and work together to achieve common goals. For blacks, such cooperation is not possible without equal citizenship and just treat- ment in all dimensions of American life. But blacks should not insist that their particular grievances be addressed inde- pendently of measures designed to en- sure justice and opportunity for all. There are non-blacks, including whites, who also need government to protect them and provide economic opportunity. He calls on the white community to acknowl- edge that black disadvantage is caused in part by discrimination, past and present. Nonetheless, he thinks we should address these inequities not through race-speci½c policies but through enforcement of non- discrimination laws and universal poli- cies that create more opportunity for all. The famous Philadelphia speech on race ends with an anecdote about two campaign workers, one white and one black, a story Obama says he ½rst told on King’s birthday at Ebenezer Baptist Church, where both King and his father had served as pastor. The lessons we are to take from the story are, I believe, these: whites who lack economic security should not blame blacks and Latinos but, rather, should seek them out as allies against the injustices caused by corporate greed, cor- rupt political leadership, and the super- wealthy who want to keep all bene½ts of economic growth for themselves and their progeny; blacks and Latinos, in turn, should not allow their racial griev- ances and sense of victimhood to prevent them from forming productive alliances with whites who have similar problems. Obama’s fundamental goals of racial equality and integration are worthy. Moreover, his assessment of current ra- cial realities and their historical roots is, I believe, accurate. However, I am trou- bled by his proposed way forward. I see four related problems, all of which stem from Obama’s failure to heed King’s pre- cept: to use means as pure as our ends. First, Obama asks blacks to shoulder too much of the burden of racial conciliation and demands too little of whites. Indeed, in the name of interracial unity, his ap- proach would actually reward white re- sistance to racial-justice measures. Sec- ond, Obama’s vision would require that we use morally suspect tactics, includ- ing compromising with, and remaining silent in the face of, injustice and racial prejudice. Third, setting aside their ques- tionable moral standing, the means Obama advocates are not aligned with his stated ends of racial equality and in- terracial fraternity, appearances notwith- standing. Finally, his strategy, though perhaps it would secure some interme- diate and worthwhile goals, might in- hibit our ability to reach the ultimate objectives of racial justice and inter- racial comity. 102 Dædalus Winter 2011 Justice & Racial Conciliation Obama has consistently stated that both current discrimination and the leg- acy of past discrimination help explain existing racial inequalities and black dis- advantage, and he believes these injus- tices have not been adequately addressed. If this interpretation is correct, then blacks’ sense of grievance–their continu- ing anger–is warranted. Of course, when this anger becomes rage and thus leads to cathartic violence or irrational hatred of all whites, which it sometimes has, it is not just counterproductive but abhor- rent. It is not hard to see why whites would be put off by such anger, especially those with a demonstrated commitment to racial justice. But when properly tar- geted and proportionate to the wrong that has elicited it, anger can be politi- cally constructive and a healthy sign of self-respect. It can open one’s eyes to similar injustices suffered by others; it can inspire one to take action; and, when understood to be widely shared, it can lead to collective mobilization. Indeed, a lack of anger among persons unfairly treated and burdened by injustice would be disquieting, suggesting that the afflict- ed had either given up hope or lacked self-respect, that they had succumbed to cynicism or surrendered to injustice, and that they had ceased to put up a ½ght. Jus- ti½ed indignation should not alienate whites. And if whites respond to this kind of anger with resentment toward racial minorities, dismissing their just claims for redress as a desire for handouts or excuses for their own failings, then the darker races should be angry about this reaction, too, and deeply suspicious. I suspect that some of the opposition to racial justice measures runs deeper than the desire of economically vulnera- ble whites not to lose further ground in an economy that no longer satisfactorily rewards their hard work. It also springs from their desire to keep racial minori- ties in a subordinate or disadvantaged position in relation to whites as a group. Though they are reluctant to admit it publicly (and maybe even to themselves), some whites seem determined to hold on to their comparative advantages; they view policies that promote the cause of racial justice as threats to white domi- nance.13 On grounds of self-respect, blacks should not seek a political solu- tion to the problem of racial inequal- ity that compromises with or yields ground to this sentiment. This attitude must not be accommodated, worked around, or ignored. In both “A More Perfect Union” and The Audacity of Hope, Obama rightly points out that Republican politicians and right-wing demagogues have long exploited white anger over welfare and af½rmative action and white fear of black crime. Where he falters is in failing to hold accountable working-class whites who scapegoat blacks and Latinos for problems caused by corporate and polit- ical elites. He might believe such scape- goating is racist; calling it racist, however, might seem unwise or divisive. Perhaps he is simply counseling disadvantaged racial minorities to swallow their anger, bite their tongues, and console them- selves with the thought that economic causes underlie resentment toward non- whites. He wants racial minorities to recognize what they share with low- to moderate-income whites: a common interest in altering these damaging economic forces. However, it is unreasonable and im- practical to expect racial minorities sim- ply to overlook or excuse such racist atti- tudes. How can they regard reactionary whites as allies if these whites will not confront their own racism? How can peo- ple of color work together with whites who believe that blacks and Latinos have caused the economic problems that the Dædalus Winter 2011 103 Tommie Shelby p p p p p white working class faces? Whites who scapegoat darker peoples do not yet see who the common enemy is; therefore, they cannot be relied on as allies in the ½ght against that enemy. In this way, Obama’s compromise with white racial resentment cannot achieve his stated aim of interracial unity. But let us suppose that this kind of rac- ism is a minor problem, one that can be adequately contained with vigorous en- forcement of civil rights laws. The real problem, Obama might argue, is that many whites believe that policies aimed at correcting racial injustices are contrary to their economic self-interest. They har- bor no ill will toward racial minorities; nor are they attracted to white national- ist ideas. They simply do not want to pay the costs associated with ½ghting or cor- recting racial injustice. As King emphasized, we cannot possi- bly realize our ultimate ideals if we allow this stance to reign unchallenged. We all must accept that justice, including the correction of injustice, comes at a cost– though one well worth paying. Any effort to respond effectively to racial injustice will inevitably cost whites something. Indeed, it will cost many racial minori- ties as well. For example, given residen- tial segregation patterns, there is no way to abolish de facto segregated schools without either integrating neighborhoods or busing some students to schools out- side their neighborhoods. Why should all the kids who are bused be racial mi- norities? Though it would mean aban- doning King’s ethical ideal of integration, we could try to improve urban public schools without regard to their racial makeup, but that would take a lot of resources, which means higher taxes, including higher taxes for whites. Many whites dislike af½rmative action policies because such measures offend their sense of fairness.14 But if we aban- don that set of policies (which some states already have), then any serious effort to deal with black educational and employment disadvantages will require us to devote more resources to the task, which again means higher taxes, including higher taxes for whites. These costs cannot be escaped–at least not if we intend to take racial justice seriously. One response, not without merit, is to insist that the wealthy should bear these ½nancial burdens; those who are themselves struggling economically should not. This tactic would mean col- lectively pushing for a more progressive tax scheme and higher estate taxes. But many middle-class and working-class whites do not favor this approach either; presumably, they doubt they would bene- ½t from such efforts–though some might say it has more to do with their legitimate opposition to “big government.” Obama’s response to this political reality is to combat the legacy of racial injustice by advocating universal mea- sures that aim to help the members of all racial groups, including whites. The idea is that if whites will bene½t, and the pol- icies are not explicitly tailored to aid or appease “angry” racial minorities, we can gain greater support for progressive goals. But even with backing from a number of whites, this strategy would intentionally obscure the morally impor- tant difference between creating more opportunity for all and remedying the effects of past racial injustices. From a moral point of view, these are not the same goals, even though they are com- patible and might both be furthered by the same policy. Obama advocates uni- versal policies that he believes would, as a by-product, reduce glaring racial dis- parities. But he purposefully refrains from construing these policies as racial redress. Therefore, whites are not re- quired to concede the legitimacy of 104 Dædalus Winter 2011 Justice & Racial Conciliation blacks’ grievances. To establish genuine racial conciliation, though, whites must willingly support policies that reduce racial inequality because doing so is what racial justice demands. Some would reply that if universal pol- icies will reduce racial disparities and im- prove the lives of minorities, there is no good reason to insist that race-speci½c policies be used instead. But the question is not which policies will most effectively reduce racial inequality; rather, it is why race-targeted policies are off the table. There is nothing intrinsically wrong with policies designed to help speci½c groups of people rather than everyone. From the standpoint of justice, we should not have to conceal the intent behind the im- plementation of such policies. Sometimes speci½c classes of persons (women, dis- abled persons, immigrants, rural resi- dents, victims of natural disasters, and so on) have needs that require specially tailored remedies. Indeed, so-called uni- versal policies are not really universal since they are not meant to help every- one, just those who have been socioeco- nomically disadvantaged by recent gov- ernment action and changes in the struc- ture of the economy. It is at least possible that the black urban poor is another group in need of special intervention. Again, it seems that the only reason to preemptively rule out such remedies is that they would arouse the unjusti½ed hostility of many whites. Nor is the issue whether speci½c poli- cies should be unmistakably labeled “for poor black people” or “to reduce racial disparities.” Policies designed to help all those who are unfairly disadvantaged, regardless of race, are also justi½ed and, given the overlapping interests involved, no doubt easier to enact. In our determi- nation to heal black wounds, we must not ignore the fact that others are suffer- ing, too. As King reminds us: “As we [black people] work to get rid of the eco- nomic strangulation that we face as a re- sult of poverty, we must not overlook the fact that millions of Puerto Ricans, Mex- ican Americans, Indians and Appalachian whites are also poverty-stricken. Any se- rious war against poverty must of neces- sity include them.”15 Rather, the issue is whether we can openly defend a policy on the grounds that it is, at least in part, a response to racial injustice and still garner wide support for it. If we cannot gener- ate such support, especially among whites, what does such an outcome say about the state of race relations and the possi- bility for further racial progress in this society? If we have good reason to sus- pect that a signi½cant number of whites seek to hold on to their advantages– despite the fact that some of these have been gained because of a history of racial injustice –or, worse, that a signi½cant number of whites want to keep racial minorities trapped in an inferior social position, then people of color have reason to re- sent this lack of support and to withhold solidarity from those who would deny them what they are due. Moreover, we should not have to pay off–in essence, to bribe–the white ma- jority in order to secure justice for racial minorities. Already, many whites refuse to accept the costs associated with achiev- ing racial justice. Now, in order to reduce racial inequalities caused by nearly four centuries of injustice, we must adopt only those measures that provide whites with material bene½ts? The moral perversity of this approach should be readily appar- ent. Blacks ought to demand that their fellow citizens not only acknowledge that black disadvantages are caused, at least in part, by past and ongoing injustices– a position that Obama himself articu- lates–but they should also continue to insist that their fellow citizens demon- strate a commitment to remedying these Dædalus Winter 2011 105 Tommie Shelby disadvantages, even if the necessary remedies do not bene½t these citizens directly. This admittedly dif½cult route is the only path to true racial concilia- tion. There is no bypass. If, despite his lofty rhetoric, Obama’s vision is less about achieving racial jus- tice and interracial fraternity than sim- ply making disadvantaged racial minor- ities somewhat better-off materially– using whatever means, morally tainted or not, that are available–his vision has obvious merit. It offers a pragmatic strat- egy for navigating hazardous racial waters in a way that could improve the socioeco- nomic circumstances of disadvantaged racial groups. If this political maneuver works, numerous people, including many members of racial minority groups, will receive much-needed help. However, if Obama’s racial philosophy is to be understood as an updated version of King’s vision–a recalibration to ½t the racial realities of our time–then it leaves much to be desired. Judged along- side King’s transformative vision of ra- cial equality and integration, Obama’s philosophy is morally de½cient and un- inspiring. Relying as it does on dissimu- lation and subtle bribes, it does not keep faith with King’s precept: to use means as pure as our ends. Obama’s vision would ask racial minorities to give up on true racial equality and to form bonds of solidarity with whites who refuse to rec- ognize blacks’ legitimate demands for redress. It fails to insist that whites carry their fair share of the burden to end ra- cial inequality. And it tries, futilely, to build interracial fraternity on the basis of overlapping material interests rather than on a shared commitment to justice. Perhaps we should not expect Obama to be a moral leader on issues of race. After all, he is a black elected of½cial who largely depends on other elected of½cials to enact domestic policy. He is therefore constrained by a sometimes re- calcitrant and racially divided populace. It is no doubt dif½cult to insist that one’s fellow citizens rise above their unjusti½ed anger, prejudices, and sel½shness if, to get their votes and campaign donations, one must remain silent in the face of, or even reward, these very attitudes. That Obama has not openly defended the need to reduce racial inequality and ghetto poverty on grounds of justice but has instead relied on stealth methods and “universal” policies is revealing. It shows that he believes he must accommodate race-based hostility and illegitimate white group interests to make modest improvements in the lives of disadvan- taged racial minorities. Regrettable and distasteful as it is, perhaps this is the price that must be paid to protect the weak and vulnerable from grave harm. But such actions should be seen for what they are: moral compromises necessi- tated by the imperative to meet urgent needs. They should not be cast or inter- preted as recti½cations of racial injus- tice or stepping-stones to interracial fraternity. 106 Dædalus Winter 2011 Justice & Racial Conciliation endnotes 1 For helpful feedback on earlier drafts, I thank Lawrence Blum, Gerald Early, Andrew Fine, Lani Guinier, Randall Kennedy, Lionel McPherson, and Jessie Scanlon. 2 Martin Luther King, Jr., “I Have a Dream,” in A Testament of Hope: The Essential Writings and Speeches of Martin Luther King, Jr., ed. James M. Washington (New York: Harper- Collins, 1991), 217–220. Dædalus Winter 2011 107 Tommie Shelby 3 Martin Luther King, Jr., Where Do We Go from Here: Chaos or Community? (Boston: Beacon Press, 1968), 11. 4 Martin Luther King, Jr., Why We Can’t Wait (New York: Signet Classic, 2000), 124; emphasis in the original. 5 Ibid., 127–128. 6 Martin Luther King, Jr., “The Ethical Demands for Integration,” in A Testament of Hope, ed. Washington, 117–125. 7 King, “I Have a Dream,” in A Testament of Hope, ed. Washington, 219. 8 King, Where Do We Go from Here, 54. 9 I should clarify my interpretive method used in analyzing Obama’s vision. It is general- ly understood that in order to be elected and stay in of½ce, politicians often use deceit; sometimes they lie. For the purposes of this essay, I take Obama’s considered public statements at face value. I assess the vision itself, a vision that many, including many racial minorities, support or ½nd attractive. I make no claims about whether the vision is offered in good faith, about the authenticity of Obama himself, or about the extent to which his actual policy choices and political tactics square with his stated vision. 10 Barack Obama, The Audacity of Hope: Thoughts on Reclaiming the American Dream (New York: Crown, 2006), 232. 11 The speech, both in transcript and video form, can be found at http://www .barackobama.com/speeches/. 12 An of½cial transcript of the speech can be found at http://www.whitehouse.gov/ the_press_of½ce/Remarks-by-the-President-to-the-naacp-Centennial-Convention -07/16/2009/. 13 This claim is not uncontroversial, but it does have substantial empirical support. See Donald R. Kinder and Lynn M. Sanders, Divided By Color: Racial Politics and Democratic Ideals (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996); Jim Sidanius and Felicia Pratto, Social Dominance: An Intergroup Theory of Social Hierarchy and Oppression (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999); David O. Sears, Jim Sidanius, and Lawrence D. Bobo, eds., Racialized Politics: The Debate about Racism in America (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2000); Lawrence D. Bobo and Mia Tuan, Prejudice in Politics: Group Position, Public Opinion, and the Wisconsin Treaty Rights Dispute (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2006). 14 The case that af½rmative action is not unfair is forcefully made in Bernard R. Boxill, Blacks and Social Justice, rev. ed. (Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Little½eld, 1992), chap. 7; and Ronald Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2000), chaps. 11–12. 15 King, Where Do We Go from Here, 132. work_4o3w6wkocvgzfpwkgtuatvdifu ---- Microsoft Word - Explaining Prolonged Silences in TJ FINAL Manuscript.docx                City, University of London Institutional Repository Citation: Kovras, I. (2013). Explaining Prolonged Silences in Transitional Justice: The Disappeared in Cyprus and Spain. Comparative Political Studies, 46(6), pp. 730-756. doi: 10.1177/0010414012463879 This is the accepted version of the paper. This version of the publication may differ from the final published version. Permanent repository link: http://openaccess.city.ac.uk/13106/ Link to published version: http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0010414012463879 Copyright and reuse: City Research Online aims to make research outputs of City, University of London available to a wider audience. Copyright and Moral Rights remain with the author(s) and/or copyright holders. URLs from City Research Online may be freely distributed and linked to. City Research Online: http://openaccess.city.ac.uk/ publications@city.ac.uk City Research Online http://openaccess.city.ac.uk/ mailto:publications@city.ac.uk 1     Explaining Prolonged Silences in Transitional Justice: the disappeared in Cyprus and Spain Iosif Kovras Comparative Political Studies, 46(6), 730-756. Abstract The article examines why some post-conflict societies defer the recovery of those who forcibly disappeared as a result of political violence, even after a fully-fledged democratic regime is consolidated. The prolonged silences in Cyprus and Spain contradict the experience of other countries such as Bosnia, Guatemala and South Africa, where truth recovery for disappeared/missing persons was a central element of the transition to peace and democracy. Exhumations of mass graves containing the victims from the two periods of violence in Cyprus (1963-1974) and the Spanish civil war (1936-1939) was delayed up until the early 2000s. Cyprus and Spain are well suited to explain both prolonged silences in transitional justice and the puzzling decision to become belated truth seekers. The article shows that in negotiated transitions, a subtle elite agreement links the non-instrumental use of the past with the imminent needs for political stability and nascent democratization. As time passes, selective silence becomes an entrenched feature of the political discourse and democratic institutions, acquiring a hegemonic status and prolonging the silencing of violence. Keywords: Transitional Justice; Cyprus Conflict; Spain; Enforced Disappearances; Negotiated Transitions; Post-Transitional Justice; Politics of Memory Introduction Although Federico García Lorca is a famous desaparecido (disappeared) of the Spanish civil war, he and approximately 30,000 ‘forgotten’ Republican victims are still lying in mass graves.1 Lorca’s fate epitomizes a central debate in contemporary Spanish society: should the country ‘unearth’ the truth about the civil war (and search for the bodies of the disappeared) or is it better to continue to ‘silence’ the divisive past? Spain is not the only Mediterranean country dealing with the past. During the two waves of violence in Cyprus, namely, the inter-communal violence (1963-1974) and the subsequent Turkish invasion (1974), approximately 2,000 Greek-Cypriots and 2     Turkish-Cypriots went missing. Disappearances were political acts deployed by both communities to cleanse the island of the presence of the ethnic ‘Other’ an effort to fulfil official political objectives. Until quite recently, there has been little effort to recover the bodies – or the truth. Since the 1970s, the phenomenon of enforced disappearances and the ensuing demand by relatives to acknowledge the truth have shaped the development of transitional justice2 in societies emerging from conflict or authoritarianism. The unprecedented grassroots mobilization in several South American countries of the relatives of desaparecidos seeking the acknowledgment of truth resulted in the first official bodies mandated to establish an authoritative version of human rights abuses in the mid-1980s (Neier 1999:40). For example, the strenuous efforts of the ‘Madres de Plaza de Mayo’ in Argentina led to the establishment of CONADEP, a body much like a truth commission with specific emphasis on the desaparecidos; similar coordinated efforts by relatives culminated in truth commissions in Bolivia, Chile and Guatemala, to name only a few. Since then, truth commissions have become a central tool of transitional justice (Hayner 2002). Moreover, the persistent efforts of the relatives’ associations led to landmark legal decisions, gradually constructing an international normative context which reserves a central position for ‘truth’ and enforced disappearances. The most significant recent development is the 2006 International Convention for the Protection of All Persons from Enforced Disappearance (Scovazzi and Citroni 2007). The Convention is the first universal instrument of its kind and represents a breakthrough; it ascribes the inalienable right of the relatives of a missing persons to ‘know the truth’ (art. 24, par. 2) 3 regarding the fate of the disappeared and the conditions of their disappearance. Hence, although the right to truth is still emerging in international law 3     and is not explicitly stated in international treaties (Mallinder 2008:163), the crime of enforced disappearances creates specific rights to truth for victims’ relatives in several treaties. It is in this revised normative context that such concepts as transitional justice, reconciliation and truth recovery have become central components of the policy- making agenda. Note, for example, the recent decisions by international organizations, most importantly the UN, to draw from a standard transitional justice toolbox in their peace-building initiatives (UN 2004). Given this, it is not surprising that a growing number of post-conflict countries choose human rights trials and other policies of accountability to comprehensively address the violent past, leading to a ‘justice cascade’ (Lutz and Sikkink 2001). Even more interestingly, these normative pressures encourage societies to overturn prolonged silences, even several decades after transition, a phenomenon called post-transitional justice (Aguilar 2008; Collins 2010). In the midst of this burgeoning change, Cyprus and Spain pose a complex dilemma. Contrary to the experience of other countries with disappeared/missing persons, such as Bosnia, Chile and Guatemala, where the mobilization of (civil) society to recover the missing persons was a central element of the transition to democracy, Cyprus and Spain remained (selectively) silent for a remarkably long period after their respective democratic governments were consolidated and are only now unearthing bodies and truths. Interestingly, although Latin American societies had limited access to legal and institutional tools, they mobilized earlier and more effectively to address the demand for truth than did Spain and Cyprus, even though the latter were members of influential international organisations. One would expect 4     societies with advanced legal instruments to be more proactive and effective in resolving human rights issues but this was not the case. Why do certain societies defer the acknowledgment of human rights problems even when democracy has been fully consolidated? How is this silence constructed, maintained and perpetuated? How (if at all) do transitional justice settlements persist over time? Finally, what explains the recent efforts of a growing number of countries like Spain and Cyprus to establish the truth and overturn prolonged silences, even several decades after the transition? It is argued that an early elite consensus, frequently informed by political learning from past experiences, links the non-instrumental use of the past with the political and security priorities of the nascent regime. Ultimately, this leads to strong institutionalization. As time passes, a ‘linkage trap’ is constructed, whereby selective silence becomes a well-entrenched and hegemonic feature of the political discourse and democratic institutions. Eventually, this hegemonic linkage narrows the variety of alternative policies and sidelines dissenting voices. Paradoxically, this linkage frequently provides the necessary tools for domestic truth seekers to acknowledge past human rights abuses, albeit in the long term. The article contributes to the growing (post)transitional justice debates, by highlighting the importance of domestic political actors in shaping or limiting external normative pressures. The decision of political elites to overturn prolonged silences is often informed by electoral, security symbolic and other domestic political considerations rather than driven by normative adaptation to external pressures. This is a gradual and often reversible process, influenced by the structure of domestic politics. The article also notes that the phenomenon of post-transitional justice is enhanced by unprecedented developments in forensic science. Uncontested forensic 5     evidence legitimizes previously excluded voices, thereby encouraging truth-seeking initiatives to mobilize, even belatedly. The article begins with a critical review of the literature of transitional justice, focusing on the absence of an analytically rigorous presentation of central working concepts. Drawing on the innovative tools of ‘elite framing’, it then explains the above-mentioned puzzles in Cyprus and Spain and sheds light on the causal mechanism through which silence over past humanitarian issues is constructed and perpetuated. It concludes with insights relevant to the study of (post)transitional justice. Enforced Disappearances and Truth Recovery in Transitional Justice Although the concept of truth recovery in transitional settings has gained currency over recent decades, it has been used to refer to a wide range of different – even contradictory – phenomena. It remains contested whether truth recovery constitutes a means to a higher end (i.e. reconciliation) or an end/value in itself. It is equally undetermined if truth refers to a process (i.e. truth-telling) or an outcome (i.e. report of a truth commission). Nor have scholars determined whether the scope of truth is individual (micro-truth) or social (macro-truth). In essence, the literature fails to address a number of ontological, epistemological and political problems. To get around this problem, this article adopts a bifurcated view of truth recovery. On the one hand, narrow truth recovery is used to refer to a minimalist conception of truth , more precisely, to forensic evidence related to the whereabouts of the disappeared/missing persons. Since the early 1990s forensic exhumations have become a conventional tool of international institutions in addressing the individual (narrow) demand for truth (Stover et al 2003:663-664). On 6     the other hand, wider truth recovery, indicates the official and unofficial efforts of societies emerging from conflict or authoritarian regimes to democratize the process of dealing with the past (Smyth 2007), by broadening the accessibility to the public discourse of previously excluded voices. These range from truth commissions, to tribunals, traditional justice, community-story-telling initiatives and official apologies. Needless to say, these conceptions of truth are not contradictory and frequently overlap. Based on the ‘Peace Accord Matrix’ of Kroc Institute, Table 1 identifies a number of countries as truth-seeking or non-truth seeking, relating this to the type of settlement reached – negotiated or non-negotiated. A careful examination of the table reveals the explanatory strengths and limitations of transitional justice literature. Three main groups of countries emerge from the table. [Insert Table 1 about here] In the first group, shown in the bottom boxes, the absence of a comprehensive peace settlement, as in the case of Eritrea-Ethiopia, can explain the decision to abstain from addressing the past. Elsewhere the total victory (or collapse) of one of the parties in conflict, as in the Philippines, creates conducive conditions for the winning side to decide whether to address the past. Meanwhile, in places like Cambodia or Timor-Leste where international involvement constitutes a central feature of transition/peace-building initiatives, transition is followed by some form of (narrow or wide) official acknowledgment of the problem of disappearances, most significantly through the establishment of retributive models of accountability. The proactive involvement of international institutions includes the contribution of material resources, as well as logistic support to undertake exhumations or establish war 7     crimes tribunals and truth commissions (Sriram 2004:25; UN 2004) and reflects an entrenched commitment to the normative principles of transitional justice. A normative thread seems to be linking a growing number of scholars who insist that societies in transition who address human rights violations, such as enforced disappearances, are more likely to strengthen the rule of law, prevent recourse to self- help justice, develop respect for human rights culture and educate citizenry in democratic practices (Elster 2004; Méndez 2001:32; Minow 2002). The growing use of the tool of human rights trials in most societies where international organizations are engaged in peace-building, bolsters the argument that the norm of accountability for grave human rights violations has created the ‘justice cascade’ mentioned above (Sikkink and Walling 2007; Lutz and Sikkink 2001). A second group, at the top left of the table, involves cases of negotiated transitions/peace settlements, where the transition was followed by some sort of acknowledgment of the problem of the disappeared.4 It seems that a significant number of countries have opted to acknowledge human rights abuses despite the fragility of the peace/democratization processes. In fact, certain landmark cases that have shaped contemporary debates on transitional justice, such as Argentina and Chile, could have been included in this box. It is revealing that all societies who experienced a pacted transition and decided to come to terms with their past – with the exception of Croatia – chose the establishment of a truth commission over measures of retributive justice. In essence, this column reaffirms the view of a growing number of scholars who include truth commissions as novel and superior tools in the transitional justice toolbox (Hayner 2002). Truth commissions have historically been seen as ‘second-best’ alternatives, located somewhere between the impossibility of retributive justice prohibited by the pacted nature of the transitions 8     and the growing demand for truth in societies with missing persons (Neier 1999:40). More recently, truth commissions have been transformed; their functions include the ability to restore the dignity of victims, to uproot long-standing myths that bolster violence and cultures of victimhood (Rotberg 2000) and to break the cycles of violence (Minow 2002), thereby becoming a central instrument of transitional justice (Brahm 2007;Hirsch 2007). But that is not the whole story. One would expect that in the post-1989 period, when the tools (including binding legal instruments, the centrality of human rights on the international agenda and DNA testing) were available to recover the (narrow or wider) truth about missing persons, more societies in transition would have acknowledged the truth and provided societal closure. But as the third group, shown at the top right of the table reveals, more than half the countries who experienced a negotiated transition have resisted – for the time being – these external pressures. In fact, as the experiences of Mozambique and Northern Ireland indicate, they have primarily designed policies based on amnesties and silence. A number of realist scholars subscribing to the ‘logic of consequences’ (Snyder and Vinjamiri 2003) have long argued that because transitions/peace agreements are fragile processes, any effort to comprehensively address the past may upset ‘spoilers’ who perceive truth recovery initiatives to be blatant scapegoating and thus endanger the transition (Vinjamuri and Snyder 2004:225). In essence, these scholars insist that scrutinizing the past is not a normative decision but a political one and, as such, any measure that could contribute to the stability and consolidation of the regime could legitimately be used, even if this requires the adoption of amnesties, impunity, forgetting and silence (Cobban 2006; Mallinder 2008; Mendeloff 2004). 9     Spain and Cyprus are outlier cases and do not fit well into the table. Spain would have initially been included in the top right quadrant. During the transition to democracy (1975), Spanish society and political elites decided to establish a ‘pact of silence’ and literally and figuratively bury these complex issues. Still, in a remarkable volte face, 70 years after the conclusion of the civil war and almost 30 years after the consolidation of democracy, Spain started digging into its past (Aguilar 2008), moving it to the top left box. For its part, Cyprus is the only case where despite the absence of a political settlement of the conflict, a successful mechanism has been established to address the demand for (narrow) truth recovery of Turkish-Cypriot and Greek-Cypriot missing. It therefore makes sense to use these two societies to comprehensively test the central arguments of transitional justice literature. With the exception of Northern Ireland, the literature of transitional justice has focused on ‘success stories’ (i.e. where truth recovery is central in the transition) such as South Africa, the former Yugoslavia and Guatemala (Thoms et al 2008). Little notice has been taken of cases where the truth recovery for missing persons and transitional justice has been absent, such as Cyprus and Spain. Moreover, by focusing explicitly on the period of transition, or immediately following it, the literature has failed to notice that although societies during transition may decide to defer the solution of human rights issues this does not necessarily mean that a demand to acknowledge this will not emerge in the future. Furthermore, the transition in Spain and the cessation of hostilities in Cyprus took place well before the above mentioned normative turn in the 1990s. Rather, they occurred at a time when foreign intervention for human rights was minimal, thereby making these two countries instructive examples on how societies can manage humanitarian problems in the absence of the ‘international factor’. Finally, the time- 10     lag permits us to draw safer conclusions, test alternative hypotheses and examine causal patterns of silence/non-silence over human rights abuses, than if we use more recent cases. For all these reasons, Cyprus and Spain are well suited to explain both prolonged silences in transitional justice and the decision to become belated truth seekers. Political learning, negotiated transitions and silences In societies emerging from conflict, the guidelines for what will be remembered and what will be excluded from public discourse are drawn up during the transitional period. Therefore, the study of transitions provides useful insights into the (non)solution of human rights problems and the long term effects of transitions. As Diagram 1 indicates below, elite consensus is significantly facilitated – often dictated - by transitions that result from a pact between the major political forces. In cases of pacted transitions, there is a need to set a least common ideological denominator upon which to build the consensus for the new political regime. [Diagram 1 here] A decision to silence contentious incidents of the past, such as the Spanish Civil War, or to ‘selectively remember’ the past in a way that accentuates a culture of victimhood, as in Cyprus, is frequently identified as the most appropriate basis for consensus in transitions to democracy. More than politics is at stake here. The burgeoning field of ‘memory studies’ has shown that a common feature of post- traumatic societies is the conscious decision to forget certain painful aspects of the past (Brewer 2010:147;Connerton 2008:60). In a notable case-study commonly used in transitional justice literature, post-World War II (West) Germany’s transition in the 11     1950s is characterized by the social amnesia of Germans – forgetting what they did and also what was done to them (Misztal 2005:1327). A subtle agreement is frequently reached between parties previously in conflict to ‘link’ the non-use of the bitter past to the political arena in exchange for a commitment to the new democratic political regime. Since negotiated transitions are perceived to be second-best alternatives for all parties, contentious issues like truth recovery are often excluded; public debate raises the issue of responsibilities and might easily become a ‘blame game’, endangering the whole agreement. For example, in Northern Ireland, the IRA remains sceptical of opening a formal truth recovery process on the issue of the disappeared, as this would raise the thorny issue of responsibilities (Guelke 2007:285). In this way, silence or selective memories become ingrained in political discourse. As noted, eventually, the elite framing becomes institutionalized and hegemonic; this may be the most effective path to peace, stability and democratic consolidation, but it decreases the prospect and scope of truth recovery. The process of consensus-building described here is often facilitated, even dictated, by the painful experiences of the past which act as political lessons at crucial historical junctures, such as transitions. 5 According to Bermeo, ‘crises often force people to re-evaluate the ideas that they have used as guides to action in the past. The changed ideas may relate to tactics, parties, allies, enemies, or institutions’ (1992:274). As Bermeo sees it, a lesson can be learned by considering similar experiences of other countries in the international arena (horizontal lesson) or considering a similar preceding period in a society’s history (vertical lesson) (ibid). Elite settlements, although providing a conducive environment for promoting democracy and peace, not to mention the ideal environment for resolving urgent 12     problems (economy, reconstruction, institution-building), are achieved at the expense of the quality of the emerging democracy. Negotiated transitions tend to concentrate power in the hands of a few political elites and inhibit open democratic procedures; they restrain the development of a vibrant civil society and slow the development of political and civil rights (Encarnación 2003; Licklider 1995:685; Linz and Stepan 1996:56). The most significant side-effect of ‘pacted transitions’ is the demobilization of civil society. Main sources of truth-seeking in post-conflict/post-authoritarian regimes are vocal civil society groups associated with the victims; in negotiated transitions, like Cyprus and Spain, these remained silent. As noted above, in both Cyprus and Spain an early elite consensus to link the non-instrumental use of the past with the need for political stability led to the creation of a hegemonic discourse. Once a frame becomes hegemonic, inconvenient questions that contravene or challenge it are excluded from public debate. As Ian Lustick says, hegemonic discourses ‘exclude outcomes, options or questions from public consideration’ (1993:121). This does not mean that frames are permanent or immutable: new legal, scientific, economic or political developments may force elites to slightly revise their proffered frame to sustain its hegemonic role and prevent its crumbling. However, if the intensity and significance of the new developments outshine the ability of frame-makers to incorporate them smoothly in the existent frame, then the hegemonic frame loses its explanatory value and collapses. Methodology Elite framing is a useful tool to study the policy outcomes that prevent truth recovery. The framing process has two analytical components. The first stems from the need to 13     identify the source(s) of the problematic situation and attribute responsibility: this could be termed ‘legitimizing framing’ (Benford and Snow 2000). It presumes that the present situation is unjust, and grievances are due to the actions of another agent or conditions outside the control of the ‘in-group’ (Gamson 1992; Klandermans 1997). The second, ‘motivational framing’, derives from the need to change the problematic situation; it leads to the creation of a strategy to accomplish change (Benford and Snow 2000). Framing ‘select[s] some aspects of a perceived reality and make[s] them more salient in a communicating text, in such a way as to promote a particular problem, definition, causal interpretation, moral evaluation, and/or treatment recommendations’ (Entman 1993:52). The primary function of frames is to ‘organize experience and guide action’ (Snow et al 1986:464); thus, a core element of the framing process is the degree of instrumentalization in the definition of an issue. The framing process determines ‘reality’ because of its ability to highlight certain aspects of reality while ignoring others (Benford and Snow 2000). As Entman aptly notes, ‘The frame determines whether most people notice and how they understand and remember a problem, as well as how they evaluate and choose to act upon it’ (1993:54). Because policy-makers and ordinary people deploy these simplified mental images to interpret social events and choose among alternative courses of action (Tetlock 1998:876), framing is a useful tool for analyzing certain aspects of a conflict, in this case, truth recovery for missing persons.6 In this article, I employ an innovative, multi-method approach to ‘elite framing’ (Benford and Snow 2000), drawing on an extensive and comprehensive study of parliamentary speeches in two countries over the last three decades. This analysis is coupled with process tracing to identify the causal mechanism by which 14     the specific elite framing adopted during transition prevented the scope of truth recovery in Cyprus and Spain (George and Bennett 2005:215). In the wide-ranging archival work that preceded the analysis, I read parliamentary debates, seeking to trace the construction of elite discourse(s). I also had limited access to classified documents from the Cyprus House of Representatives and memos prepared for the Ministry of Foreign Affairs of the Republic of Cyprus. Finally, I examined party documents, such as electoral programmes and party memoranda. All these helped me to determine the development of the political discourse. The interviews I conducted with politicians shed light on why certain policies were chosen over others at specific junctures; and my interviews with individuals with privileged information allowed me to ‘triangulate’ my hypotheses. The study of parliamentary debates has several advantages. For one thing, it allows the analyst to pinpoint a certain framing which is adopted at a very specific time; actors cannot retrospectively change their positions to suit temporal changes in context (Loizides 2009). For another, it facilitates process-tracing, or the construction and maintenance of elite discourse over the long-term. Spain: Disappeared and El pacto de silencio What becomes apparent from the Spanish parliamentary debates7 is that the issue of the desaparecidos was not raised until the early 2000s.8 This prolonged silence poses a methodological problem in the elaboration of the elite framing. To overcome it, I pursue two complementary paths. First, I analyze the debates on other victims’ groups: those mutilated in the civil war, the widows and children of the fallen and ex- prisoners. I consider the difference between the treatment of their demands and the silence over the issue of desaparecidos and relate this to elite framing. Second, I 15     examine the debates on the Amnesty Law (1977), generally perceived to be the founding tenet of the transition. The two sets of analyses, coupled with my interviews of members of the designated parliamentary commission and my study of electoral programs overcome this methodological concern. The debate on the Amnesty Law of 1977 is revelatory of ‘legitimizing framing’. In it, the civil war is presented as a period of ‘collective madness’ where both sides committed heinous crimes. The attribution of responsibility is strictly avoided: clearly, there is no ‘rational’ actor to blame for the immense tragedy (Aguilar 2002). An example of this diagnostic framing appears in the words of the spokesperson of the governing party, Unión de Centro Democrático (UCD); in a 1978 reference to the debated law on pensions for widows and orphans, Bravo de Laguna Bermudez says: [T]hose widows and orphans that today we talk about….are not merely widows or orphans of the communists, of the socialists, or anarchists, but widows and orphans of the tragic Spain … We can give different explanations about what happened between 1936 and 1939, but in any case, it was a national tragedy. (Parliamentary Debates Num.141, 23/11/78:5576-8) He goes on to proffer strategies to alter the situation (‘motivational framing’). In effect, two central framing strategies link the silence on humanitarian issues with the legitimacy of the transition: the establishment of a wide political consensus to bury the divisive past and achieve reconciliation – seen as a precondition for democratic consolidation; and the adoption of an instrumental rationale for redressing victims groups’ (material) needs for closure. The element of learning from past experiences is evident in the speeches on the Amnesty Law and the Draft Law. The former Law is framed as the symbolic 16     closure of a prolonged period of divisions and the beginning of a new democratic era. During its debate, a representative of the Socialist Party insisted: ‘Today is the date, in which finally, the civil war is buried’ (Parliamentary Debates Num.24, 14/10/77:965- 8). Throughout the Parliamentary records, the need to bury the past is seen as the distilled experience of painful lessons, even by the representatives of the ‘defeated’, most notably communist leader Santiago Carillo (Parliamentary Debates Num.5, 27/7/77:73-76). In the interviews I conducted with members of the Designated Parliamentary Committee for drafting the Law on Historical Memory, in 2004, almost all still subscribed to this prognostic framing, saying that an agreement to bury the past was mandatory at the time (Anonymous Interviews, 6 May 2009 and 18 May 2009). The other tenet of motivational framing highlights the instrumental rationale of accommodating the victims groups’ demands. More specifically, reparations are granted to certain groups not as an acknowledgment of their suffering or their contribution to a noble cause but to comfort the disaffected, including reparations to widows and orphans (Parliamentary Debates Num.141, 23/11/78:5575-6) and military pensions (Royal Decree 6/1978). In part, these are acts of benevolence – not justice. They are perceived as solving problems not covered by the Amnesty Law; therefore, they are treated as solutions that will enable closure (punto final) and accelerate the processes of national reconciliation and democratic consolidation (Aguilar 2008:420). Still, desaparecidos are excluded from this framing. Oddly enough, at approximately the same time as the amnesty debates, unofficial exhumations were carried out in Spain. My archival research shows that from 1977 and throughout this first step towards democracy, exhumations took place around the country. In fact, a popular magazine of the time, Interviú,9 featured detailed coverage of the efforts of 17     the relatives of desaparecidos to exhume the graves and provide their loved ones with a decent burial (Interviú 21/12/1978; 3/01/1980). Although in other transitional places (Latin America), these grassroots processes have led to strong social movements, in Spain, they lost momentum and succumbed to the overriding hegemonic discourse. Why was the issue of desaparecidos silenced when the demands of other victims groups were accommodated? I have two overlapping responses, the first focusing on the top echelons and the second on the grassroots, both related to the side- effects of the specific elite framing. First, political exhumations (‘narrow truth’) or policies of acknowledgment (‘wider truth’) for the desaparecidos and the political violence would have raised questions of political responsibility. Asking and answering the question ‘who did what to whom?’ had the potential to derail democratic consolidation. Therefore, any truth-seeking initiative was out of the question because it contradicted the raison d’être of the proffered framing, namely, to abstain from using the past as a political argument in debates. A second overlapping explanation considers the meagre participation of Spaniards in civic associations, a phenomenon described by Omar Encarnación as ‘civic anemia’ (2001:63). More than 20 years after the consolidation of democracy, only one in three Spaniards belongs to any voluntary association, levels similar to the post-communist regimes of Eastern Europe (ibid). For one thing, the legacy of the (pacted) transition led to the demobilization of the civil society, thereby hindering truth-seeking. For another, an endemic feature of Spanish political culture is the penetration/control of all sorts of civic associations by political parties, primarily through financial means (Encarnación 2003). To some extent, political parties have determined the agenda of the associations and defined their scope. As the early elite 18     framing became institutionalized and ‘hegemonic’, it narrowed the conception of national interest at the top and silenced grassroots practices that could contravene it. An indication of the hegemonic status of the discourse is its institutionalization in legislation and legal decisions. Ryan says that in 1979, an individual involved in an unofficial exhumation was reprimanded for carrying out ‘illegal exhumations’ (Ryan 2009:123). The legal institutionalization of this hegemonic belief is even obvious in the contemporary wave of exhumations. In a recent motion, Judge Baltázar Garzón argued that the systematic nature of the crime constitutes a crime against humanity, and therefore the 1977 Amnesty Law is inapplicable to cases of enforced disappearances (Motion 399/2006). The possibility of overturning the founding tenet of the transition, namely, the Amnesty Law, sparked heated political debate and opened up the prospect of Garzón’s expulsion. The case of Garzón can be fully understood only within the wider post- transitional justice context in Spain (Aguilar 2008). More precisely, since the early 2000s, several grassroots organizations of relatives have mobilized to unearth their desaparecido ancestors, provide them with a decent burial, clear their reputation and acknowledge the corresponding (republican or democratic) version of truth about the Spanish civil war (Gálvez-Biesca 2006; Ferrándiz 2009). 10 The mobilization of the generation of the grandchildren of the disappeared exerted bottom-up pressure on the Socialist government, leading to the passage of the above-mentioned Law on Historical Memory which addressed central issues of transitional justice: denouncing Franco’s regime; banning public symbols that commemorate Franco or his allies; mandating local governments to finance exhumations of mass graves; declaring ‘illegitimate’ the summary military trials held during the civil war and Francoist 19     dictatorship; opening up military archives; and offering other measures of moral, symbolic and economic repair to all victims of the war (Law 53/2007). In other words, more than three decades after the consolidation of democracy in Spain, a specific framing was ingrained in political institutions, the political system and legislation. Simply stated, its hegemonic status prevented truth recovery. Surprisingly, however, the prolonged silence was finally broken. Proof of this is the passage of the Law on Historical Memory and its fuelling of media and public debates. Cyprus: selective memory and missing frames Tracing the elite framing of the problem in the RoC over the past decades reveals a number of downplayed or silenced issues. Take, for example, the official definition of the missing. Until 2003, a missing person was considered to be a ‘Greek-Cypriot who is still missing since the July 20th 1974, due to the Turkish invasion…and the state has no positive information that s/he died’ (Law Number 77/1979). Two interesting features of motivational framing are evident in this definition. First, the beginning of the problem of missing persons coincides with the Turkish invasion (20/7/1974), thereby indicating a conscious decision to causally link the issue of the missing with the invasion. Since 1974, 12 resolutions by the House of Representatives have assigned sole responsibility to Turkey; all were adopted unanimously (Resolutions Number 37/1975; N.46/1978; N.58/1980; N.113/1992;N.124/1997). Second, the Turkish-Cypriots who went missing as a result of the atrocities of Greek-Cypriot paramilitaries in the 1960s (Patrick 1976) are excluded, even though they are citizens of the Republic. 20     In other words, selective memory (or selective oblivion) became a founding tenet of the pact that facilitated the transition to peace and democracy in the RoC after the 1974 invasion. References to cases of missing persons, either Greek-Cypriots or Turkish-Cypriots preceding the Turkish invasion, would have seriously delegitimized the predominant discourse which identifies the Turkish invasion as the cause of the problem. Motivational framing can explain the tactics of political elites in the addressing of the problem of the missing. They used two overlapping framing strategies: one emphasizing national unity and reconciliation by strengthening the institutions of the Republic as the only way to overcome the legacy of intra- communal division of the past within the Greek-Cypriot community and restore credibility to the RoC; the other using the symbol of wounds opened by the Turkish invasion to accentuate a ‘culture of victimhood’ and enable the construction of a new common basis of ‘unity’ for the Greek-Cypriot community. Although the Turkish invasion is used as the focal point of the framing, it was preceded by growing intra-communal violence within the Greek-Cypriot community culminating in a short coup ousting President Makarios.11 Leftists, frequently treated as traitors, were the targets of violent attacks during the anti-colonial struggle of EOKA   (Εθνική Οργάνωση Κυπρίων Αγωνιστών - National Organization of Cypriot Fighters);12 these peaked during the coup (Papadakis 1993). A number of civil society initiatives representing the relatives of those killed have recently emerged demanding that the state apologize for the human rights violations of leftists (Ireton and Kovras 2011). The legacy of intra-communal violence was so traumatic that it continues to create political cleavages within the Greek-Cypriot community. Nevertheless, in the overall ‘Cyprus problem’, even left-wing parties who suffered from nationalist 21     violence have subscribed to the frame prioritizing ‘national unity’. For example, on the first anniversary of the coup, when the memories of the intra-communal violence were still fresh, the leader of communist party AKEL officially declared that his party would ‘keep the flag of patriotic unity high’ (Parliamentary Debates 15/7/1975: 581). The Cypriot Communist party echoed PCE’s conciliatory tone in Spain, mentioning the need for concessions (‘silences’) to pave the way for democracy. The Turkish invasion led to a revised framing, one focusing on unity and the traumas of the invasion. The missing became the central symbol of ongoing suffering, and political elites invested political capital in this framing. The official name of the designated parliamentary committee on missing persons (established in 1981), the Committee on Refugees-Enclaved-Missing and Adversely Affected Persons (discussed in greater detail below), underscores this political strategy. By linking all aspects of victimhood triggered by the Turkish invasion, it was expected to frame the problem in human rights terms, thereby enhancing international sympathy for the Greek-Cypriot negotiating position in the search for a political settlement to reunify the island. As might be expected, the elite framing, in combination with the (de facto) division of the island in Cyprus facilitated the creation of a ‘highly censorious environment’, one ‘marked by taboos, intolerance and vilification of views deviating from the predominant governmental discourse and the official views of history’ (Faustman 2009:34). As in Spain, this culture has fettered the development of a vibrant and vocal civil society (Mavratsas 2003) which, as noted above, is a source of truth-seeking. Even the official organization of the relatives of the missing has interpreted human rights through the lens of national interests. In other countries with disappeared or missing persons, such organizations are the main sources of truth 22     seeking; but in the Greek-Cypriot community, they blocked truth recovery (Kovras and Loizides 2011). For example, in the mid-1990s, the relatives’ association objected to the government’s intention to exhume common graves in two Greek-Cypriot cemeteries on the grounds that this would lead to a ‘cover-up’ of the problem (ibid). Despite the absence of a political settlement, in 2004 a bi-communal agreement was reached to resume the activities of the hitherto ineffective Committee on Missing Persons (CMP). ‘De-linking’ humanitarian issues like the missing – where the Republic of Cyprus had a moral advantage – was previously considered likely to weaken the overarching Greek-Cypriot political strategy for the reunification of the island. However, lessons learned from past policy failures by chief policy-makers, technological advancements that supported a revised policy and the domestication of new (legal and human rights) norms,13 all contributed to the resumption of the CMP. It has now become the most successful bi-communal project on the island (UN 2007). By August 2010, 690 bodies had been exhumed and 248 identified (CMP 2010). In addition, although the elite framing retained its founding tenets, it became less rigid and began to acknowledge the victimization of Turkish-Cypriots. Paradoxically, a dual framing process has facilitated the exhumations and the demand for (narrow) truth recovery. On the one hand, although the wave of exhumations is seen to reaffirm the dominant discourse of victimhood – i.e. every exhumation is an evidence of the Turkish aggression – there is strong incentive to encourage the effective working of the CMP. At the same time, the slightly revised framing that encompasses the Turkish-Cypriot missing, has led to institutional measures that introduce the (relatives of the) Turkish-Cypriot missing as legitimate political actors. This development has transformed the normative context within which domestic actors interact, leading to the support of the CMP even by actors or politicians who 23     previously had reservations. Despite the remaining political stalemate, the developments on the missing have instilled in the public and political discourse critical re-evaluation over responsibilities for the past – an element previously ‘missing’. Lessons for (post)transitional justice The study finds that an early elite consensus and its institutionalized discourse is a double-edged sword in negotiated transitions. On the one hand, the deep institutionalization of the consensus excludes dissenting voices and prevents early truth recovery. On the other hand, it may be a necessary evil to achieve a minimum level of democratic consolidation and peace. Labelling this a ‘linkage trap’, I note that in negotiated transitions, a subtle elite agreement links the non-instrumental use of the past with the imminent needs for political stability and nascent democratization. Gradually, this silence is ingrained in the political institutions and the political culture; ultimately, this framing acquires a hegemonic status that is hard to challenge. But in the long term, this silence may be a necessary precondition for democratic consolidation. Alternatively put, there is an inherent paradox in consensual institutions: they are oriented towards reproducing the consensus (hegemonic belief) which silences the victims and civil society at large, but at the same time, they cultivate democratic institutions which provide the tools necessary for domestic truth seekers (such as civil society groups) to promote truth recovery and (post)transitional justice, albeit, in the long term. Given this logic of consequences, political parties representing or affiliated with victims’ groups frequently hesitate to deal with the past, even if they assume power in the nascent democratic regime. The cases of PSOE and AKEL, in Spain and 24     Cyprus respectively are not exceptional. The consecutive Socialist governments (1981-1989 and 1993-2004) in Greece, while representing a significant number of those defeated in the Greek civil war have abstained from addressing the past. The same applies to Chile. In the aftermath of the 1989 referendum that ousted Pinochet, the centre-left Concertación coalition governed for four terms but made only marginal moves towards official acknowledgment of the past (Sandbu 2010). Political parties representing the defeated or past victims may prefer to disappoint their electoral constituents rather than trigger instability and endanger overarching objectives (i.e. democratic consolidation, economic development or reconstruction of state infrastructures). However, this is just one part of the story, since at different post-transition periods, these same parties may decide to break the silence and campaign in the interests of victims groups. For example, during his Presidency in Argentina (2003- 2007), Néstor Kirchner introduced measures calling for greater scrutiny of the past, most notably by declaring the ‘full-stop’ and ‘due obedience’ laws as null and void, as well as reopening trials for human rights abuses – including disappearances (Economist 2003). Similarly, in Uruguay, despite two referendums that rejected the annulment of the amnesties for human rights abuses during the military from 1973 to 1985, President Vázquez campaigned to abolish the amnesty law, arguing that it violated Uruguay’s obligations under international human rights treaties (Economist 2010a). Hence, silence is not an irreversible feature of national politics and collective memories. In fact, there is a growing trend in post-traumatic societies to revise the pacts of silence, even after a considerable delay, which reflects the broader normative turn in international politics. In the period preceding the end of the Cold War the 25     overarching priorities of maintaining global order and stability made amnesties and silence over human rights abuses constitutive elements of peace agreements (Newman et al. 2009). Since then, though, the global diffusion of human rights norms (Risse and Sikkink 1999) has increasingly dictated the inclusion of human rights provisions into peace settlements. As Christine Bell’s systematic study of more than 600 peace agreements since 1990 has shown, the emerging normative consensus perceives amnesties as an exception to the norm of accountability (2008:243). New normative requirements on the content of peace settlements are explained by the proactive role of the most influential international institutions in combination with the emergence of vocal transnational advocacy networks which exert pressure for their implementation (ibid). In essence, these external normative pressures have rendered blanket amnesties obsolete, changing the nature and the content of elite bargaining in peace processes and democratic transitions (Lutz and Sikkink 2001). The growing deployment of normative tools to address the past in peace agreements is also evident by the decision of an increasing number of countries undergoing negotiated transitions to deal with their violent past, a phenomenon reflected in increased number of truth commissions (Hirsch 2007). This revised normative framework not only informs the content of pact- making, but, as the experience of several South American societies has indicated, it legitimizes domestic truth-seeking actors to exert bottom-up pressure in a way that overturns enduring amnesty laws and challenges decades’ long silences (Collins 2010). In other words, the agenda of international politics (and law) has considerably changed since the historical examples of Cyprus and Spain. The new norms prevent silence from being institutionalized and bring an end to oblivion and denial in societies with well-entrenched cultures of silence. In the period preceding the 26     normative turn of 1990s, it would have been unimaginable for any Spanish government to pass a law that would address several (post)transitional justice measures or challenge the legitimacy of the Amnesty Law of 1977 – perceived as the founding tenet of the post-Francoist Spanish democracy. The landmark memory law in Spain should not be attributed exclusively to external influences. It also resulted from the sustained efforts of a number of grassroots groups who had been trying since the early 2000s to unearth the bodies of the desaparecidos of the civil war. These efforts were ultimately embraced by influential domestic allies, including political parties, judicial authorities and media, and resulted in officially implemented measures of (post)transitional justice (Ferrándiz 2009). Similarly in Cyprus, the resumption of the CMP was preceded by the strenuous efforts of bureaucrats within the Ministry of Foreign Affairs who perceived the external influences as an opportunity to implement a policy of (narrow) truth recovery. However, this policy has not led (yet) to the crumbling of the hegemonic silence – only its substantial revision. The experiences of Cyprus and Spain reveal that the role of domestic actors is crucial in taking advantage of (or resisting) external influences; even when a decision to overturn silence is made, this is not a linear or predetermined process, but gradual progress with many pauses and backward steps. Brazil verifies this; 25 years after the end of the dictatorship, the proposal of the popular President Lula to establish a truth commission on the disappeared triggered a fierce reaction from the military and was subsequently withdrawn (Economist 2010b). This is a central feature of other post- transitional justice societies, such as Chile and El Salvador (Collins 2010). External opportunities depend on domestic politics and vice versa. This point echoes Putnam’s ‘two-level game’ theory: international pressure ‘expands domestic 27     win-sets’, and as such constitutes a necessary condition for a policy shift, but ‘without domestic resonance’ this is insufficient (1988:430). The decision of political elites to revise a well-entrenched framing is often shaped by electoral, security, symbolic and other political considerations, rather than explained exclusively by normative adaptation. Drawing on the same theoretical framework, Martin and Sikkink have highlighted the importance of domestic constituencies in filtering external pressures in several Latin American countries (1993). Although the study acknowledges the power of external normative pressures in bringing about post-transitional justice and the erosion of prolonged silences, it also highlights the pivotal role of domestic politics in utilizing or resisting these normative influences, a point frequently disregarded by the prescriptive orientation of the literature. Most importantly, the study fits in with a broader trend towards bridging the gap between the international and comparative politics (Caporaso 1997); it shows how international norms have come to revise the nature of pact-making, while highlighting the importance of domestic actors and institutions. Another issue raised by the comparative analysis of Cyprus and Spain relates to the nature of truth in transitional settings. Even the most celebrated venues for screening the past, such as truth commissions or trials, analyze/incorporate individual ‘truths’ through a kaleidoscopic view of the past which seeks to establish a new mental framework to make sense of complex and confusing past events (Wilson 2003:370). Frequently, the mandates of truth commissions delimit the scope of enquiry, either by focusing exclusively on the study of specific human rights violations or by considering a very specific period of violence (Chapman and Ball 2001:4). For example, some transitional states have mandated truth-finding mechanisms to investigate only disappearances, excluding other crimes, such as 28     torture, arbitrary detention or sexual abuses of women, as the cases of Argentina and Uruguay reveal (ibid). In this way, truth-seeking initiatives contribute to a narrative construction which privileges certain memories, victims’ groups or political parties at the expense of others. Trials and truth commissions frequently exclude, obscure or marginalize other accounts that contravene this overarching framework. Therefore, it is important to highlight that while truth seekers challenge hegemony, they also construct a new one, and this new hegemony may be full of blind spots. In Cyprus and Spain, the advancement of forensic sciences has made an important contribution to truth discovery. On the one hand, forensic evidence establishes hard facts about the past violence that legitimizes previously excluded voices. On the other hand, forensic evidence from exhumations creates more (discursive) space for multiple – but equally legitimate -- truths to enter public debates. The ability to unearth the (narrow) truth about the past in a scientifically sound way paved the way for the acknowledgment of the suffering of the Turkish- Cypriot missing. Forensic truth coupled with the global normative context encourages the emergence of multiple versions of truth about the past. This enhances the prospects of (narrow or wider) truth recovery in post-conflict settings and suggests the need for overturning prolonged silences. Conclusion In negotiated transitions, a subtle elite agreement linking the non-instrumental use of the past with the political and security priorities of the transitional society is often achieved. As time passes, a ‘linkage trap’ is constructed, where selective silence over the past becomes a well-entrenched feature of the political discourse and democratic institutions. As soon as this framing becomes hegemonic, dissenting voices are 29     silenced; it also narrows the conception of national interest and inhibits the solution of human rights issues, even when new windows of opportunity open. At first glance, we conclude that this situation leads to a deadlock. However, as the hypothesis of ‘linkage paradox’ shows, in the long term, the linkage of (i.e. the silence on) human rights issues to the elite pact that serves as the founding tenet of transition becomes the most efficient way to unearth the truth. More precisely, this silence enables the consolidation of strong democratic institutions which, in turn, provide the institutional tools to (domestic) truth-seekers to put forward a comprehensive truth recovery, when such a societal demand emerges. A policy of reviewing the past cannot be implemented without societal consensus that this is a priority. The fascinating transformation of an inoperative humanitarian body for more than two decades into the most successful bi-communal project in Cyprus, and the vocal demand of the generation of the grandchildren of the desaparecidos, in Spain to unearth the remains of their grandparents 70 years after the conclusion of the civil war reflect the emergence of a new societal consensus. In both countries, domestic actors challenged the long-standing hegemonic silence, reaffirming the growing phenomenon of post-transitional justice in international politics and reflecting the new normative turn seen round the globe.14 Bibliography Aguilar Paloma (2008) ‘Transitional or Post-Transitional Justice? Recent Developments in the Spanish Case’, South European Society and Politics, vol.13(4), pp. 417-433. Aguilar Paloma (2002) Memory and Amnesia. The Role of the Spanish Civil War in the Transition to Democracy, London: Berghahn Books. Bell Christine (2008) On the Law of Peace: Peace Agreements and Lex Pacificatoria, Oxford:Oxford University Press Benford, Robert & Snow, David (2000) ‘Framing Processes and Social Movements: An Overview and Assessment,’ Annual Review of Sociology 26: 611-39 Bermeo, Nancy (1992) ‘Democracy and the Lessons from Dictatorship’, Comparative Politics, Vol. 24(3), pp. 273-291 30     Brahm Eric (2007), ‘Uncovering the Truth: Examining Truth Commission Successes and Impact’, International Studies Perspectives, Vol. 8, pp.16-35. Brewer John (2010) Peace Processes. A Sociological Approach, London:Polity. Caporaso A. James (1997) Across the Great Divide: Integrating Comparative and International Politics’, International Studies Quarterly, Vol41(4),pp.593-592 Chapman Audrey and Ball Patrick (2001) ‘The Truth of Truth Commissions: Comparative Lessons from Haiti, South Africa and Guatemala’, Human Rights Quarterly, Vol.23(1), pp. 1-43 Cobban Helena (2006) ‘International Courts’, Foreign Policy, No.153, March-April, pp.22-28. Collins Cath (2010) Post-Transitional Justice. Human Rights Trials in Chile and El Salvador, Pennsylvania: Pennsylvania State University Press. CMP, Committee on Missing Persons (2010) Fact Sheet, August 2010, Also available at: http://www.cmp-cyprus.org/nqcontent.cfm?a_id=1 Connerton Paul (2008) ‘Seven Ways of Forgetting’, Memory Studies, Vol1(1), pp.1- 59. Economist (2003) ‘A Full Stop Removed’, 368(8340):33 Economist (2010a) ‘Human Rights in Uruguay: Take three’, 24 November. Economist (2010b) ‘Don’t Look Back: The Army Blocks a Truth Commission’, January 7. Elster Jon (2004) Closing the Books: Transitional Justice in Historical Perspective, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Encaranción Omar (2001) ‘Civil Society and the Consolidation of Democracy in Spain’, Political Science Quarterly, vol.116(1), pp. 53-79. Encarnación Omar (2003) ‘The legacy of Transitions: Pact-making and democratic consolidation in Spain’, Estudio/Working Paper 2003/193, also available at: www.march.es/ceacs/ingles/publicaciones/working/archivos/2003_193.pdf Entman, Robert (1993) ‘Framing: Toward Clarification of a Fractured Paradigm,’ Journal of Communication 43(4): 51-58 Faustman Hubert (2009) ‘Aspects of Political Culture in Cyprus’, in Ker-Lindsay and Faustman Hubert (eds), The government and politics of Cyprus. Peter Lang, Oxford pp. 17-44. Ferrándiz Francisco (2009) ‘Fosas Comunes, Paisajes del Terror’, Revista de Dialectologia y Tradiciones Populares, vol. LXIV, no.1, pp.61-94. Gálvez-Biesca Sergio (2006) ‘El Proceso de la Recuperación de la Memoria Histórica en España: Una aproximación a los movimientos sociales por la memoria’, International Journal of Iberian Studies, vol.19(1), pp. 25-51. Gamson, William (1992) Talking Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. George L. Alexander and Bennett Andrew (2005) Case Studies and theory- Development in Social Sciences. Cambridge, Mass., MIT Press. Guelke Adrian (2007) ‘The Northern Ireland Peace Process and the War Against Terrorism: Conflicting Conceptions?’, Government and Opposition, Vol.42(5), pp.272-291. Hayner Priscilla (2002) Unspeakable Truths. Facing the Challenges of Truth Commissions, London, Routledge Hirsch Ben-Josef Michal (2007) ‘Agents of Truth and Justice. Truth Commissions and the Transitional Justice Epistemic Community’, David Chandler and Volker Heins (eds.) Rethinking Ethical Foreign Policy. Pitfalls, Possibilities and Paradoxes, pp. 184-205, London: Routledge. 31     Interviú, (1978) ‘Navarra: Fusilados por Dios y por España’, 21 December 1978, issue 136 Interviú (1978) ‘Navarra: Fusilados por Dios y por España’, 21 December 1978, issue 136; Interviú, ‘17 Pueblos recuperan 211 cadáveres. Legionarios fusilados por falangistas 3 January 1980, issue 190; Interviú, NAVARRA 1936 (2) Los verdugos de la Cruzada’ Interviú, (1980) ‘17 Pueblos recuperan 211 cadáveres. Legionarios fusilados por falangistas 3 January 1980, issue 190; Interviú, NAVARRA 1936 (2) Los verdugos de la Cruzada’ Ireton Kathleen and Kovras Iosif (2011) ‘Non-apologies in Post-Conflict Settings:the Case of Post-Colonial Cyprus’, Time and Society (forthcoming) Klandermans, Bert (1997) The Social Psychology of Protest. Oxford: Blackwell Kovras Iosif and Loizides Neophytos (2011) ‘Delaying Truth Recovery for Missing Persons’, Nations and Nationalism, (forthcoming). Licklider, Roy (1995) ‘The Consequences of Negotiated Settlements in Civil Wars: 1945-1993’, The American Political Science Review, Vol.89 (3), pp. 681-690. Linz, Juan and Stepan, Alfred (1996) Problems of democratic Transition and Consolidation. Southern Europe, South America, and Post-Communist Europe, Baltimore:John Hopkins University Press. Loizides G. Neophytos (2009) ‘Elite Framing and Conflict Transformation in Turkey’, Parliamentary Affairs, Vol.62(2), pp. 278-297. Lustick, Ian (1993) Unsettled States, Disputed Lands: Britain and Ireland, France and Algeria, Israel and the West Bank. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Lutz Ellen and Sikkink Kathryn (2001) ‘The Justice Cascade: The Evolution and Impact of Foreign Human Rights Trials in Latin America’, Chicago Journal of International Law, Vol.2(1), pp.1-34. Mallinder Louise Maria (2008) Amnesty, Human Rights, and Political Transitions: Bridging the Peace and Justice Divide, Oxford: Hart Publishing. Martin Lisa and Sikkink Kathryn (1993) ‘U.S. Policy and Human Rights in Argentina and Guatemala, 1973-1980’," in Double-Edged Diplomacy: International Bargaining and Domestic Politics, edited by Peter Evans, Harold Jacobson, and Robert Putnam, Berkeley:University of California Press, pp:330-362. Mavratsas, Caesar (2003) Εθνική Οµοψυχία και Πολιτική Οµοφωνία. Η ατροφία της Ελληνοκυπριακής κοινωνίας των πολιτων στις απαρχες του 21ου αιώνα. Athens:Katarti. Mendeloff David (2004) ‘Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, and Post-Conflict Peacebuilding: Curbing the Enthusiasm?’. International Studies Review, Vol.6, pp. 355-380. Méndez E. Juan (2001) ‘National Reconciliation, Transnational Justice, and the International Criminal Court’, Ethics and International Affairs, Vol. 15(1), pp. 25-44. Minow Martha (2002) ‘Breaking the Cycles of Hatred’, In Minow Martha (ed.) Breaking the Cycles of Hatred: Memory, Law and Repair, pp. 16-75, Princeton, Princeton University Press. Misztal Barbara (2005) ‘Memory and Democracy’, American Behavioral Scientist, Vol.48(10), pp.1320-1338. Neier Aryeh (1999) ‘Rethinking Truth, Justice, and Guilt after Bosnia and Rwanda’, in Carla Hesse and Robert Post (eds.), Human Rights in Political Transitions: Gettysburg to Bosnia , pp.39-51, New York, NY: Zone. 32     Newman Edward, Paris Roland and Richmond Oliver (2009) ‘Introduction’, in New Perspectives on Liberal Peacebuilding, Newman Edward, Roland Paris and Richmond Oliver (eds), United Nations University Press, pp.3-25. Papadakis, Yiannis (1993) ‘The Politics of Memory and Forgetting’, Journal of Mediterranean Studies, Vol3(1), pp.139-154 Putnam Robert (1988) ‘Diplomacy and Domestic Politics: The Logic of Two-Level Games’, International Organization, Vol.42(3), pp.427-460. Risse Thomas and Sikkink Kathryn (1999) ‘The Socialization of International Human Rights Norms into Domestic Practices: Introduction’, in The Power of Human Rights: International Norms and Domestic Change, Risse Thomas, Ropp Steven and Kathryn Sikkink (eds), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp.1-38. Rotberg Robert (2000) ‘Tryth Commissions and the Provision of Truth, Justice, and Reconciliation’, in Truth V. Justice. The Morality of Truth Commissions. Edited by Rotberg I. Robert and Thompson Dennis, pp. 3-21, Princeton, Princeton University Press. Ryan Lorraine (2009) ‘For Whom the Dominant Bell Tolls: The Suppression and Re- emergence of Republican Memory and Identity in Spain’, in Laura Rorato and Anna Saunders (eds.) The Essence and the Margin. National Identities and Collective Memories in Contemporary European Culture, Amsterdam: Rodopi, pp.119-134. Sandbu Martin (2010) ‘Chile Six Months since the Earthquake’, Financial Times, 28 August 2010. Sant Cassia, Paul (2005) Bodies of Evidence. Burial, Memory and the Recovery of Missing Persons in Cyprus. Oxford, Berghahn Books (Paperback Edition). Sikkink Kathryn and Walling Carrie Booth (2007) ‘The Impact of Human Rights Trials in Latin America’, Journal of Peace Research, Vol.44(4), pp.427-445. Scovazzi Tullio and Citroni Gabriela (2007) The Struggle Against Enforced disappearance and the 2007 UN Convention, Leiden:Martinus Nihoff Publishers Snyder Jack and Vinjamuri Leslie (2003) ‘Trials and Errors. Principle and Pragmatism in Strategies of International Justice’. International Security, Vol. 28(3), pp. 5-44. Sriram, Chandra Lekha (2004) Confronting Past Human Rights Violations: Justice vs. Peace in Times of Transition. New York, NY: Frank Cass. Stover Eric, Haglund William and Margaret Samuels (2003) ‘Exhumation of Mass Graves in Iraq Considerations for Forensic Investigations, Humanitarian Needs, and the Demands of Justice’, JAMA, 2003;290(5):663-666 Tetlock Philip E, (1998) ‘Social Psychology and World Politics’ in Daniel .T. Gilbert, Susan T. Fiske, and Gardner Linzey, Eds., The Handbook of Social Psychology, 4th ed, Vol. 2 (New York: Oxford University Press, 1998). Thoms Oskar, Ron Jamer and Paris Ronald (2008), ‘The Effects of Transitional Justice Mechanisms’, Center for International Policy Studies, Working Paper, April 2008 UNFICYP (2007), ‘The UN in Cyprus. An Inter-Communal Survey of Public Opinion by UNFICYP’, also available at: http://www.unficyp.org/nqcontent.cfm?a_id=1324 United Nations (2004) ‘The Rule of Law and Transitional Justice in Conflict and Post-Conflict Societies’, UN Security Council, S/2004/616/23 August 2004 33     Wilson Richard Ashby (2003) ‘Anthropological Studies on National Reconciliation Processes’, Anthropological Theory, Vol. 3(3), pp. 367-387. Table 1: Type of transition/settlement and truth recovery for disappeared/missing persons1         Sources: Peace Accords Matrix, Kroc Institute (http://peaceaccords.org), last accessed 2 April 2011) the Physical Integrity Rights Cingarelli and Richards Human Rights Data Set (http://ciri.binghamton.edu/) and the annual ‘Country Reports on Human Rights Practices’ of the US State Department. The first date in parentheses refers to the transition/peace agreement, the second to the implementation of the official truth seeking mechanism. 34     Diagram 1: Schematic presentation of the construction and maintenance of (hegemonic) silence                                                                                                                           1 The estimated number of remains still lying in unmarked mass graves ranges from 30,000 to 100,000 (Ferrándiz 2009) 2 This has been defined as ‘the array of processes designed to address systematic or widespread human rights violations committed during periods of state repression or armed conflict, where human rights violations are defined as extrajudicial killings, disappearances, torture, and arbitrary arrest and imprisonment’ (Olsen, Payne & Reiter 2010:805). 3 ‘Each victim has the right to know the truth regarding the circumstances of the enforced disappearance, the progress and the results of the investigation and the fate of the disappeared person’. 4 Assisted by the International Commission on Missing Persons (ICMP), Croatia has established a mechanism to exhume, identify and return the disappeared to their relatives. 5 Peter Hall provides an interesting definition of learning: ‘a deliberate attempt to adjust the goals or techniques of policy in response to past experience and new information. Learning is indicated when policy changes as the result of such a process’ (Hall 1993:278). 6 It should be mentioned that framing is not an epiphenomenon. It is not merely a reflection of reality, but a simplification of a ‘perceived reality’ (Loizides 2009). In essence, framing is the deliberate effort of different social actors to produce, guide and maintain meaning, and, as such, it is important to examine how specific political problems are framed (Benford and Snow 2000:613). By examining the framing strategies of different actors, we can establish cause and effect relationships. 7 This includes research on the parliamentary debates, questions and laws related to the issue of desaparecidos in the Spanish Congreso de los Diputados (Lower House); interviews with members of the designated inter-ministerial commission that prepared the law on the Recovery of Historical Memory in 2007; and analysis of the electoral programmes of the major nation-wide political parties since the first democratic elections after transition in 1977. 8 Although there are scattered references in the 1970s and 1980s, there are only marginal provisions for the reparations of relatives. 9 I am grateful to Professor Santos Juliá for bringing this source of information to my attention. 10 Association for the Recovery of Historical Memory. 11  15 July 1974. 12  The most important Cypriot anti-colonial armed group active in the 1955-1959 period.   35                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                 13 The ruling of the European Court of Human Rights in the fourth Interstate application of Cyprus v. Turkey (27581/94), 10 May 2001, constituted a landmark decision that influenced the policies of both Turkey and the RoC.       work_4oocwaedmfadpkec4kab74dbve ---- http://www.globalbuddhism.org/8/usarski07pdf.htm Research Article Journal of Global Buddhism 10 (2009): 321 - 349 Toward A Buddhist Theory of Justice James Blumenthal Department of Philosophy 102A Hovland Hall Oregon State University Corvallis, Oregon 97331 U.S.A James.blumenthal@oregonstate.edu Copyright Notes: Digital copies of this work may be made and distributed provided no charge is made and no alteration is made to the content. Reproduction in any other format with the exception of a single copy for private study requires the written permission of the author. All enquries to: http://www.globalbuddhism.org mailto:James.blumenthal@oregonstate.edu� Journal of Global Buddhism / 321 ISSN 1527-6457 A r t i c l e Toward A Buddhist Theory of Justice James Blumenthal Department of Philosophy 102A Hovland Hall Oregon State University Corvallis, Oregon 97331 U.S.A James.blumenthal@oregonstate.edu Abstract For more than twenty years key thinkers of Engaged Buddhism have used terms like “justice” and “social justice” quite freely. Yet despite more sophisticated discussions of other philosophical topics, Engaged Buddhists have not clearly defined what they mean by the term justice. Given that the term is one with a rich philosophical history in the West and has no direct parallel in Buddhist thought, it is incumbent upon Engaged Buddhist theorists to define what they mean when they use this term if they are to engage in any sort of meaningful dialog on justice and related issues in the international community. In this paper, to illustrate how Engaged Buddhists might begin this important line of work, I would focus on two cases. First, I will discuss John Rawls' theory of "justice as fairness" and compare that with some traditional Buddhist ideas and explore potential Buddhist thinking, responses, and adaptations. Second, I will discuss a relatively new model known as restorative justice in opposition to the pervasive use of retributive models implemented around the globe and consider the ways that Buddhism seems to lend itself quite well to "restorative" models, particularly with regard to criminal justice. Both examples mailto:James.blumenthal@oregonstate.edu� Journal of Global Buddhism / 322 are merely beginning points for discussion used to illustrate how and why Engaged Buddhists ought to participate more directly in global philosophical discourse on justice. Introduction Theoretical developments in the Engaged Buddhist movement and scholarly analysis of these have advanced substantially in the past ten years. Sophisticated treatments of issues such as non-violence, rights, and responsibilities have helped to shape increasingly important developments in this area of Buddhist thought (for example, King, 2005). For more than twenty years key thinkers in the movement have used terms like “justice” and “social justice” quite freely.(1) Yet despite more sophisticated discussions of other philosophical topics (2), Engaged Buddhist thinkers have thus far not clearly defined what they mean by the term justice. Given that the term is one with a rich philosophical history in the West and has no direct parallel in Buddhist thought, it is incumbent upon Engaged Buddhist theorists to precisely define what they mean when they use this term if they are to contribute to, or engage in any sort of meaningful dialog on justice and related issues in the international community or on the world stage. (3 Rather than attempt to sketch a history of Western philosophical treatments of justice, a project outside the scope of this paper, I will take just two examples for exploration to illustrate how Engaged Buddhists might begin this important work. First, I would like to discuss some of the ideas of one of the most prominent twentieth century American thinkers on justice, John Rawls, and suggest potential preliminary Buddhist reflections on those ideas. The specific aspect of Rawls' thought that I will highlight concerns perspectives on distributive justice – the way to determine just means for distributing the goods deemed valuable by society and/or ) Obviously the topics of justice and social justice are enormous and ones that can only begin to be discussed in this paper. Thus, my primary purpose here is simply to highlight the need for further discussion among Engaged Buddhists on this critical philosophical topic that lies at the foundation of socially engaged Buddhism. Journal of Global Buddhism / 323 individuals in society. (4 These entire discussions are not intended to draw conclusions about a Buddhist theory of justice here, but are meant to help begin the process of Buddhists entering the larger philosophical dialog on justice – one that I think is critical for Buddhists in their own internal thinking process on these issues. It is also one that I believe Buddhists will have much of value to contribute to in the larger global philosophical conversations in the future. Given the rich heritage of thought on justice in the West tracing back to Plato and Aristotle and running throughout Judeao-Christian theological and philosophical discussions, this is really meant to be a first step in opening dialog and an opportunity for Engaged Buddhist theorists to begin to consider these issues in a more sophisticated way. ) The second dimension of justice theory I will discuss as an example concerns the form of justice employed by society or the state in response to criminal activity. Here I will bracket issues concerning legal systems, and focus on current conversations by those advocating a relatively new model known as restorative justice in opposition to the pervasive use of retributive models implemented around the globe. I will begin this paper by reflecting a bit on the method one leading Engaged Buddhist thinker has taken thus far and offer some comments on that. I highlight Sulak Sivaraksa because he has probably been the most explicit, but I think his method is reflective of that of many major engaged Buddhist thinkers today. After some brief comments on methodology, I will proceed to the two examples mentioned above from Western philosophical discourse on justice for consideration. First, I will briefly outline the highlights of Rawls' notions of "justice as fairness," and his method for achieving this fairness in the construction of society, from behind what he calls the "veil of ignorance." I will use this as a stepping off point to compare his ideas with the Buddhist principle of "equanimity" to see what sort of parallels may be found, what of utility may be construed in this comparative work, and begin to consider if Rawls' ideas on the topic might be a fruitful starting point for constructing a Buddhist theory of distributive justice. I will then proceed to our second example, the question of retributive vs Journal of Global Buddhism / 324 restorative justice, and offer some reflections on potential Buddhist responses and contributions to issues that arise in such discussions on just response to criminal activity. Finally, I will offer some concluding remarks. Buddhist Resources: Where to Start? Though Buddhism has not formally discussed justice in the way that it has been discussed in Western philosophical traditions, that is not to say that ideas and principals are not present and that there is not much to draw from in Buddhist literature, ethical discussions, Buddhist descriptions about the nature of reality and its ways of functioning, as well as our ways of knowing (that is, Buddhist epistemology or pramaa.navaada thought). Much is explicit; other dimensions can be abstracted in fruitful ways. In his book, Seeds of Peace: A Buddhist Vision for Renewing Society, leading Engaged Buddhist thinker and activist, Sulak Sivaraksa, proposes a number of innovative ways Buddhists can think about and act upon systemic problems that plague our contemporary societies and situations. He is an intellectual hero for many Engaged Buddhists, and his life's work is an embodiment of the Engaged Buddhist ideals he espouses. Much of his theoretical work revolves around the question of how we are to build a just society, one that for him, by definition, embodies the basic principles of Buddhism. What does a society that embodies, or at least engenders, pursuit of Buddhism's highest ideals look like? And how are we to go about attempting to create such a society, or at least move in that general direction? His method is to begin by going to traditional literature as our primary source of wisdom on such topics. (5 To create a Buddhist model of society, we must first look into traditional Buddhist notions of social order and social justice. It is worthwhile to begin by examining the Buddhist scriptures. ( ) Sivaraksa writes: 6 ) Journal of Global Buddhism / 325 I think this method of turning to ancient Buddhist texts and scriptures has important virtues. Buddhist canonized literature and the wisdom it contains can and ought to be a rich resource for this project. (7 Considering Theories of Justice: Two Examples ) That said, our reading of those traditional sources can be fruitfully complimented by two methodological considerations that may not have been fully utilized: a rigorous historical contextualization of the sources, and a sophisticated understanding of broader discussions about justice from outside of Buddhist traditions so as to see how Buddhist ideas might fit or shape those found in extra-traditional (that is, Western) sources. Historicism deepens our understanding of meaning in context such that the ideas can be more fruitfully translated into current situations. A broad and sophisticated understanding of ideas about justice, including those outside of the Buddhist tradition opens the possibility of gathering new insights and new avenues for framing traditional Buddhist ideas that may not otherwise occur to thinkers within the tradition. It also makes a reciprocal global conversation about justice much more viable. Though the first methodological consideration is critical, in the interest of space, and because this has been discussed exhaustively elsewhere, my focus in this paper will be on the second of the methodological considerations, explorations of the long philosophical discourse stemming from outside of the Buddhist traditions. 1) Rawls on Justice as Fairness: The Veil of Ignorance With this in mind, I would now like to turn to discuss John Rawls' notion of justice as fairness. John Rawls was one of the most important political philosophers of the twentieth century. He is perhaps most famous for his theoretical strategies for setting up a just society and the distribution of goods in society (in other words, "distributive justice"). ( 8 ) The concern for constructing a just society is one that Rawls shares with Sulak Sivaraksa and many other Engaged Buddhist thinkers, though as far as I know, he has no Buddhist background. Perhaps Buddhists can profit from considering the thinking of such a leading figure, or others like him, Journal of Global Buddhism / 326 who have inherited a tradition of philosophical analysis on justice that spans more than two thousand years. Rawls is interested in the guiding principals that one could use to construct a just society. What are these principles that can be used to construct a just society? Rawls begins to describe them as follows: They are the principles that free and rational persons concerned to further their own interests would accept in an initial position of equality as defining the fundamental terms of their association. The principles so derived would then guide all further agreements in the construction of society. This process of deriving and utilizing principles of justice are referred to by his famous phrase, "justice as fairness". The question soon arises as to what it means to establish principles of justice from "an initial position of equality". Rawls proposes a hypothetical situation to do this where the free and rational persons constructing fair principles of justice would do so behind a "veil of ignorance". In other words, if one wants to determine the principles of justice for constructing a just society under Rawls' notion of "justice as fairness," then those involved in determining these principles must reflect and contribute to notions of what is fair and just from behind a veil of ignorance. Rawls describes this veil of ignorance as follows in his A Theory of Justice: Among the essential features of this situation is that no one knows his place in society, his class position or social status, nor does any one know his fortune in the distribution of natural assets and abilities, his intelligence, strength, and the like. I shall even assume that the parties do not know their conceptions of the good or their special psychological propensities. The principles of justice are chosen behind a veil of ignorance. This ensures that no one is advantaged or disadvantaged in the choice of principles by the outcome of natural chance or the contingency of social circumstance (Rawls, 1971 and 1999: 10). Journal of Global Buddhism / 327 In other words, what kind of basic principles for constructing society would I advocate if I did not know whether I would personally be an African-American male, or born into extreme poverty, or a CEO of a multi-national corporation, or of extraordinary intelligence, or physically handicapped, or lesbian, or Buddhist, or Christian, or non-religious, etc.? If I stood behind a veil of ignorance with regard to my own personal position in the kind of society I would create, it is from this basis, that we can begin to discover the basic fair principles upon which to construct a just society according to Rawls. Thus, Rawls' notion of justice as fairness emerges from behind a "veil of ignorance," with the stated goal of creating, "rules [that] specify a system of cooperation designed to advance the good of those taking part in it" (Rawls, 1971 and 1999: 4). Obviously there is much more to say about Rawls' ideas, but I believe this is a good starting point for some Buddhist reflection on justice. Many Engaged Buddhists take as one of their basic premises that the construction of a just society and/or work towards the transformation/reconstruction of our current situation is and always has been an indelible part of the Buddhist project. (9 To suggest that Buddhism has been unconcerned with the organization of society is to ignore history. Traditionally Buddhism has seen personal salvation and social justice as interlocking components (Sivaraksa, 1992: 67). ) To quote Sulak Sivaraksa again, And Robert Thurman, among the first important American Engaged Buddhist thinkers wrote, The primary Buddhist position on social action is one of total activism, an unswerving commitment to complete self-transformation and complete world-transformation... [I]t is squarely in the center of all Buddhist traditions to bring basic principles to bear on actual contemporary problems to develop ethical, even political, guidelines for action (Thurman, 1985: 120). Journal of Global Buddhism / 328 But how does one determine the contents of a just society? It seems that Buddhists are going to want to construct a model for a society that embodies, engenders, and nurtures its most important ideals – ideals such as compassion, wisdom, mindfulness, patience, tolerance, and to as great a degree as possible – freedom from suffering, among others. These are the sorts of things that Buddhists might claim "advance the good," to borrow Rawlsian language. An ideal Buddhist society it seems would be one that encourages spiritual development and moral courage, broadly construed. That does not mean everybody being Buddhist, but perhaps everybody being encouraged to achieve their highest potential, with complete and utter freedom of religion or lack thereof. This is the sort of description we find in Engaged Buddhist writings on an ideal society for which to strive. (10 We see a great deal of application of these sorts of ideas, but not as much serious work on the theoretical ground of such ideas and the actions that ensue. This has the potential to lead to dangerous consequences where the door of activities happening in the name of Buddhism is thrown wide open. Other than appeals to textual authority, there has not been a solid philosophical grounding to these ideas presented. Much can be extrapolated from words attributed to the Buddha in canonical sources, either directly, or with a little molding, but even the Buddha said that we should examine and question all his words and not just accept them on faith because they was spoken by the Buddha. All the more so when ideas are being molded to suit a new context. Dignaaga and Dharmakiirti, the two most important Indian Buddhist thinkers on logic and epistemology argue that scripture alone, while providing a basis for faith and inspiration for practitioners, is not necessarily a source of valid knowledge (pramaa.na), though they would argue that at times it could be considered equivalent to a logical inference (anumaana), which is a form of valid knowledge. My point here is that according to tradition, its ideas must be grounded in or supported by reasoning. ) So the question again arises: how do Buddhists determine the contents of a just society? If the principles Engaged Buddhists Journal of Global Buddhism / 329 want to use to construct a just society are valid, they must be able to stand the test of rational analysis or be defensible by reasoning according to the Buddha and to Dignaaga and Dharmakiirti. This seems to be what Rawls is attempting to do in some respects. He wants to construct a just society on rationally grounded principles that are fair and in the best interest of individuals and society broadly construed - that they "advance the good of those taking part in it." (Rawls, 1971 and 1999, 4). His method for discerning those principles - utilizing the "veil of ignorance" with free and rational people at the helm - seems to me to be an attempt by Rawls to construct a society on the basis of a defensible rational standard. And this method might be one with appeal to Buddhists in a modified form. I think that we can construe some conceptual parallels in the ideas behind Rawls' method for discovering the fair principles of a just society and the Buddhist notion of equanimity, though admittedly they emerge out of quite different contexts. For Rawls, the method of getting at those principles is via free and rational people considering the construction of society from behind a veil of ignorance with regard to their particular positions in that society. The fairness that emerges is ideally one of maximum benefit to the group without either sacrificing consideration of the particular situation of any individual or privileging any individual over another. This "fairness," to use Rawls' term, is maintained by one not knowing their own particular position in society during the construction period, thus guaranteeing that the principles are constructed in a context free of bias. The Buddhist ideal of equanimity is found throughout the tradition's literature. In the Pali canon there are extensive discussions of equanimity as one of the four divine abodes (bramavihaaras) where the meditator trains in viewing and treating friends, neutral persons, and enemies the same. ( 11) The aim behind this practice is to generate an attitude of loving-kindness extended impartially to all living beings - to avoid favoritism or disregard for anybody. A profound compassion develops through this contemplation of the circumstances of loved ones, neutral people, and enemies. By Journal of Global Buddhism / 330 seeing how they are all similar in their suffering and that the basis of their actions – even those we see as harming us - is largely ignorance (avijjaa, avidyaa) and afflictive emotions (kle"sa), the result is a recognition that everybody would certainly want to be rid of such obscurations that cause so much suffering if they knew the way to do it. Thus, though the details may vary, the fundamental dilemma we face and the causes behind it are quite similar. The impartiality that is the ground of this principle of equanimity seems to have many parallels with the notion of fairness developed in Rawls' theory of justice. It aims to ethically engage without personal bias. In the Mahayana literature, discussions of equanimity are equally pervasive, particularly in relation to generating the Mahayana motivation of bodhicitta, the altruistic wish to achieve enlightenment in order to benefit others. ( 12 First I will explain the stages of meditation on compassion. Begin with meditation on equanimity. Cultivate impartiality for all sentient beings by clearing away attachment and hatred. All sentient beings want happiness and do not want suffering. Consider how they have all been my close friend hundreds of times since beginningless samsara. Since there is no basis for attachment to some and hatred for others, develop equanimity for all sentient beings. Meditation on equanimity begins with contemplation of a neutral person; then also contemplate those who are friends and enemies. ( ) This Mahayana aspiration is founded in part upon equanimity, the utterly impartial mind that refrains from any bias towards or discrimination between persons with regard to compassion for their situation and the wish to personally be of maximum benefit to them, which in Buddhism of course means benefit on the path to enlightenment. The eighth century Indian master Kamala"siila, for example, discusses the cultivation of compassion in light of cultivating equanimity in the fourth chapter of his [Middle] Stages of Meditation (Bhaavanaakrama, bsGom pa'i rim bar pa): 13 ) Journal of Global Buddhism / 331 The fairness which seeks to advance the good for all members of society striven for via Rawls' veil of ignorance and the unbiased concern for others that the Buddhist notion of equanimity embodies as it may be applied in a socio-political context both have similar goals. They both aim towards achieving maximum benefit to individuals in the world while simultaneously keeping the big picture of either society as a whole or the well-being of all sentient beings under consideration. With that said, there are differences. Rawls' primary aim in advocating for justice as fairness is not soteriological at its basis, whereas the Buddhist notion of equanimity does encompass that salvific goal at its foundation. Rawls seems to want to get at the secular principles upon which one can construct a just society. The principles themselves may or may not include soteriological goals, though presumably they would be supportive of them if there were members of society with such motivations. The Buddhist notion of equanimity seems to start with the soteriological goal and secondarily may find secular applications that are also virtuous. It seems to me that the two start with different presumptions. Rawls wants to begin on secular ground but not neglect the spiritual aspirations of certain members of society. A Buddhist application of equanimity to issues of the creation of a just society would seem to begin on religious grounds, but in social-political application would not want to neglect the more secular needs and aspirations of both non-religious and religious members of society or the particular aspirations of those of other faiths. Does Rawls' method here resonate with an adoption of the Buddhist idea of equanimity as a principal ground for a Buddhist construction of a just society? Can a Buddhist fruitfully adapt Rawls' method so that it would be inclusive of the kinds of ideas and principles that would be of central importance to Buddhists? Can Rawls' "veil of ignorance" be "Buddha-ized"? If so, in what ways would Buddhists want to use Rawls as a starting point? What sort of changes would we want to make? Is there something contra-Buddhist if the guiding principle for Rawls' method is self-interest, even if the end goal is to use self interest to facilitate the Journal of Global Buddhism / 332 interest of all? If self-interest is utilized merely as a tool for coming to conclusions that serve the wellbeing of others, is there still a fundamental flaw? When combined with the veil of ignorance, isn't it just a skillful way of approaching the construction of societal rules with equanimity for the baring they may have on all members of society? Might this be a particularly skillful way for unenlightened people to go about this project? If a Buddhist were to want to come up with an adaptation that would appeal broadly to both Buddhists and non-Buddhists, then we need to think things through very carefully. For example, I think Buddhists would want to ground the Rawls' "free and rational" persons who act behind a veil of ignorance in some virtuous predispositions or considerations. Rawls seems to have confidence in an inherent tendency among such persons to engage in such a way simply by virtue of their intelligence, rationality, and freedom. I think a Buddhist may want to be more explicit. Rawls' model tends to rely on the enlightened self-interest of those behind the veil. I would imagine that a Buddhist theory of justice would want to ensure a profound and pervasive compassionate attitude as the ground upon which a just society would be built. Enlightened self-interest would be nice, but a Buddhist might have reason to doubt that actual enlightened application, even given the parameters Rawls has set up, would follow suit. Thus, perhaps in addition to being free and rational, that those behind the veil might supplement or replace the enlightened self-interest implicit in Rawls' account with explicit imperative to consider the role compassion for the suffering of individuals might play at every turn in constructing or adjudicating just principles. Rawls may consider this to be implicit, but making it explicit could be important for Buddhists. The parameters of such an imperative would need to be thoroughly considered. If there is one virtue that guides Buddhist ethics more than any other, it would be compassion for the suffering of living beings. Any Buddhist vision for a just society must both be guided by compassion in its formation and nurture its further cultivation in its application. Thus, perhaps one modification of Rawls' theory for Buddhists might be that those free and rational beings be Journal of Global Buddhism / 333 explicitly required to consider compassionately the potential suffering in various scenarios in working from behind the veil of ignorance so as to explicitly consider ways that social structures do or do not contribute to such suffering. This is just one consideration among many. My purpose here is not to solve the problem, but to raise some questions with this example. 2) Retributive vs. Restorative Justice: A Buddhist Perspective I would like to take a brief look at a second example and second dimension to philosophical discourse on justice, that of criminal justice. How might or ought a Buddhist or Buddhist society deal with crime? What might Buddhism stand to gain from participation in a larger global discourse on responses to criminal activity? And what might Buddhism have to offer to a broader global discourse on the topic? Generally speaking, the approach of most nations today toward crime is to attempt to control it, largely through dispensing punitive measures against those who violate the state's laws. This is seen as fulfilling a dual purpose: deterring future crime and enacting justice on the perpetrator of the crime already committed. In the case of prison-time as punishment, it may additionally be considered beneficial in that it takes a potentially dangerous individual out of circulation from society, thus making the society safer. This mode of justice in its varying forms is what is known in philosophical discourse as retributive justice; it enacts retribution on criminals for crimes committed. Retribution, whether that be the death penalty for murder, or extensive jail time for stealing or other crimes, is viewed as enacting justice on the criminal. They get what they deserve. Without extreme forms of punishment, its effectiveness with regard to deterrence is highly questionable. I believe that the ethics of this sort of punitive or retributive approach to justice would, in most cases, be equally questionable from a Buddhist perspective. I will discuss this shortly below. An emerging response to retributivist forms of justice, both in philosophical circles and actual implementation in select cases, is a growing movement with nuanced variations that is referred to with the over-arching label of "restorative justice". I think that a Journal of Global Buddhism / 334 Buddhist approach might resonate well with many of the ideas and approaches circulating in restorative justice discourse and that Buddhists might have important contributions to make to this discourse as well. Restorative justice aims to restore well-being and heal the wounds inflicted by the crime through a variety of means. Rather than view offenders and victims as adversaries in criminal proceedings, open communication that sees them as partners in a healing process tends to be a much more effective perspective according to advocates for restorative justice. One of the prime examples often cited for this process was the use of the Truth and Reconciliation Commission in South Africa in the wake of Apartheid which gave voice and ultimately greater comfort and healing to both victims and perpetrators. Dullah Omar, former South African Minister of Justice explained that the commission was a "necessary exercise to enable South Africans to come to terms with their past on a morally accepted basis and to advance the cause of reconciliation." ( 14 Before proceeding further in discussion of restorative justice from a Buddhist perspective, I would like to briefly summarize the plot of one particular sutta, the Angulimaala Sutta, from which I believe much can be gleaned regarding Buddhist perspectives on some of these issues. The sutta recounts the story of the encounter between the Buddha and Angulimaala, a serial killer who had been ) There are a variety of shapes and forms restorative justice might take in varied circumstances. No advocate of restorative justice views it as a one-size-fits-all solution. While prison may be a dimension to it in some cases for example, advocates of restorative justice would want to see a wholesale prison reform in most circumstances. Prison would become a place that not only protects society from dangerous individuals, but would also be a place where the incarcerated are given the opportunity and encouraged to use the time for a healing and transformative process. It would be seen as an opportunity rather than punishment. Working out the details of the shapes this might take would be a major project, but the end result would be a facility that fosters positive rather than the sort of negative transformation of inmates, as is so often the case in prisons around the world today. Journal of Global Buddhism / 335 terrorizing the local countryside in the state of Kosala by going on a murderous rampage, earning his name (Angulimaala, Finger-Garland) by wearing a garland around his neck made of the fingers of his victims. One morning, as the Buddha went on his alms round, despite repeated warnings about Angulimaala's presence in the area, he encountered him on the road. The Buddha kept walking as Angulimaala ran after him, intending to kill him. The Buddha continued to walk calmly as he was chased, but due to his supernatural powers, no matter how fast Angulimaala chased after him, he could not catch up. Finally, Angulimaala shouted at the Buddha to, "Stop," to which the Buddha replied, "I have stopped, Angulimaala, you stop too." A confused Angulimaala goes on to question the Buddha's statement to which he replies, "Angulimaala, I have stopped forever, I abstain from violence toward living beings; but you have no restraint towards things that live: That is why I have stopped and you have not." (Nanamoli, Bhikkhu and Bhikkhu Bodhi [Trans.], 1995: 771). Upon hearing this, Angulimaala was immediately struck by the Buddha's wisdom and became his disciple, requesting and receiving ordination as a bhikkhu at once. Upon hearing that Angulimaala was with the Buddha in Jeta's Grove, King Pasenadi led a cavalry of 500 men to go arrest Angulimaala. When the king arrived, he had an audience with the Buddha and respectfully asked about the whereabouts of Angulimaala. The Buddha asked the king what he would do if Angulimaala were transformed and now leading the life of a virtuous bhikkhu of good character. The king replied that he would honor and pay homage to him in an assortment of ways. The Buddha then pointed out the transformed Angulimaala, former serial killer, to the king who was amazed. The king, indeed, paid homage to Angulimaala. It was not long after that, that upon further teachings from the Buddha that Angulimaala achieved arhatship. The following morning, when on his alms-collecting rounds, Angulimaala was attacked by townspeople who, knowing of his previous deeds as the killer of their kinsmen, threw various objects Journal of Global Buddhism / 336 at him, drawing blood and breaking his begging bowl. When he discussed this with the Buddha, the Buddha told him to bear it, for he was experiencing the results of previous karmic deeds. The sutta closes with a verse recitation by Angulimaala rejoicing in his transformation due to following the teachings of the Buddha. Given my very cursory remarks about restorative justice, some basics of Buddhist philosophy, and in light of some insights we might glean from the Angulimaala Sutta, I would like to make some very preliminary comments about Buddhism and restorative justice. First, until we are all enlightened, there will probably be a need for laws. How ought a Buddhist or Buddhist society deal with crime, with the violation of laws? Most nations, modern and ancient have utilized some form of retributive justice – to exact some form of retribution on the violator of the laws. Some have argued that it is just in and of itself for people to be punished for violation of laws agreed upon by the community. Others have argued it serves as a deterrent. I don't think either of these are particularly "Buddhist" ways of thinking or compelling arguments from a Buddhist perspective. Punitive justice entails exacting harm on criminals. Causing unnecessary harm for anybody, even a criminal, seems to me to run utterly contrary to the most fundamental ideas of Buddhism. After all, did the Buddha not leave the palace in search for a cure for suffering? Are Buddhists not charged with having compassion for all living beings, even the worst among them? It is common at the ceremony for taking refuge in the Three Jewels that new Buddhists are urged to do their best to avoid causing harm or suffering to all living beings. It is hard to imagine the Buddha advocating the overt execution of suffering on individuals out of revenge or spite, or in the name of some notion of justice. Even the utilitarian argument that claims that punishment as deterrence to greater and more future crimes and suffering seems to have logical holes if one were to presume some Buddhist philosophical basics, like the notion of dependent-arising. Nothing arises without dependence on related causes and conditions. Effects have a direct relation to causes. Just as it is counter-intuitive on a large scale to bring lasting peace through war and violent means, so too is it Journal of Global Buddhism / 337 counter-intuitive, from a Buddhist perspective, to think that threats of extreme punishment will undermine the root causes of law-breaking in society. There may be relative or short-term success, but since the root causes will not be destroyed, it would be deluded to think that deterrence would actually be successful at eradicating crime on a large scale. And given the millennia-long experiment with this method and the lack of decline in crime, this Buddhist analysis seems to be proven correct. Rather than retributive or punitive justice, I think the Buddha would probably advocate a form of this new model of justice known as restorative justice in this respect and I think this can, in part, be gleaned from the Angulimaala Sutta. It does not seem that the Buddha, or the tradition as it represents itself in the Angulimaala Sutta, advocates a retributive or punitive form of justice. King Pasenadi does not see any reason to exact punishment upon Angulimaala for revenge, retribution, to create a deterrent to future crime, or for any other reason. This is due to Angulimaala's transformation into a virtuous and sincere bhikkhu who was fully reformed and posed no threat to society. Given Angulimaala's present virtuous state as a contributing member of society, to exact punishment would not only be unnecessary; but also be an immoral cause of suffering. Buddhism is first and foremost concerned with alleviating suffering and eradicating the roots of suffering. I think that a Buddhist take on the issue of societal responses to crime would be to advocate for some restorative model that would aim to both create a resolution and peace between the criminal and victim, and would aim to heal the root cause of the crime and the damage inflicted in its wake. In a sense, Buddhism would ideally like to see criminals transformed, as Angulimaala was. This further dimension of reformation is perhaps an area where Buddhists could both learn from those with more experience in restorative models and offer unique contributions as well. (15 Karma is, of course, a dimension to any Buddhist theorizing on justice that needs to be considered. Doesn't karma, although meant to be a descriptive doctrine aimed at explaining the effect of ) Journal of Global Buddhism / 338 intentions and actions of body, speech, and mind on our future experiences and states of consciousness, also describe the negative consequences of unethical behavior from a Buddhist perspective? One might ask if there is any need for state imposed punishment at all if one holds the idea of karma. Isn't karma the Buddhist theory of justice? Teachings on karma have been used successfully and probably ought to continue to be used as a motivator and teaching device on ethical behavior. Its philosophical function is to explain the causal relationship between our intentional actions and our consciousness and its future experiences rather than specifically to denote a form of reward and punishment. Technically it is not at all about reward and punishment whether under the control of a third party god , or not. It is simply an explanation of one dimension of causality from a Buddhist perspective. If karma were taken to be the beginning and end of discussion of a Buddhist theory of justice, that karma takes care of everything with regard to justice, then the Buddhist position would be a quite fatalist or determinist doctrine. It would undermine attempts to create a society that is better for the welfare of all (as is the engaged Buddhists' overarching project) because karma would be the sole factor determining outcomes. Perhaps more importantly, it might even suggest that efforts towards one's own transformation and efforts to become enlightened would be pointless. If future experience is entirely determined by past karma, it would undermine any real agency, which in turn would undermine karma doctrine itself. I think this reflects a partial understanding of karma that misses the key component of agency that really is at the heart of karma theory in the first place. Though there are teachings on the purification of karma (for example, Tsongkhapa's Byang chub lam rim chen mo [The Great Treatise on the Stage of the Path to Enlightenment]), generally speaking it is taught in texts like Vasubandhu's Abhidharmako"sa (Treasury of Knowledge, Chapter 4) that individuals will infallibly experience the fruits of their karmic acts at some future point. We see this illustrated in the Angulimaala Sutta when, even after achieving arhatship, Angulimaala is stoned by the townspeople and the Buddha tells him to bear it, for it is the fruit of his previous Journal of Global Buddhism / 339 negative karma. But such a display of "justice" made manifest is not, from the Buddhist perspective, reason not to engage in what contemporary writers might refer to as restorative models of justice. Angulimaala still strove for spiritual restoration, despite the inevitability of his karma. His restraint at this point was essentially an act of restorative work in that he was, in affect, hearing the grievances of those who suffered in the wake of his crime, an acknowledgement of his wrong doing, an expression of regret, and an apology. A Buddhist might still aim to establish a system to help to reform and heal the criminal as well as the victims out of compassion for the suffering of all. Though it may not have been called for in Angulimaala's case due to his rather remarkably rapid transformation, that is not to say that prison, appropriately conceived and implemented, might not be necessary for yet-to-be-reformed criminals. (16) Fundamental to a Buddhist approach to crime must be a recognition of an individual's capacity to transform (as Angulimaala did). I would think that the (Buddhist influenced [ 17 It seems to me that to seek punitive retribution for a crime committed is an intention and act grounded in anger, one of the three poisons (greed, anger, and ignorance) that keep individuals rooted in the sufferings of samsara according to Buddhism. This is not to say that Buddhists might not advocate for a form of imprisonment for some crimes for the dual purpose of the safety of society and a period of reformation/restoration/transformation of the prisoner. But contrary to most prison systems today that are so horrendous that criminals usually come out worse than when they went in, I believe a Buddhist model would emphasize healing the root causes behind the crime, some of which are related to material conditions in the world, but more importantly for this aspect of our discussion, are related to the mental and psychological states (or one might say, 'karmic predispositions') of the criminal. David Loy pointed out ] ) state would want to want to encourage some sort of transformation through the implementation of various programs, etc. "Punishment" ought to include measures that engender such transformation. This Buddhist-type thinking is all in line with restorative justice thinking as well. Journal of Global Buddhism / 340 quite insightfully that, The Buddhist approach to punishment, like any other approach, cannot really be separated from its understanding of human psychology and its vision of human possibility (Loy, 2001: 81). For the Buddhist, there is both a faith in the possibility of transformation and a responsibility to work towards it. I think this sentiment can be applied on secular grounds as well. In most countries this would probably take the shape of some sort of serious prison reform where the focus would be on the psychological rejuvenation of the criminal and the creation of a process for healing any antipathy between the criminal and the victim. The particular details of what such a system would look like in application are beyond the scope of this article. When I speak about potential Buddhist approaches to criminal justice, I am speaking to a large degree in the abstract. I am not speaking about the ways specific Buddhist countries or countries where the vast majority of the populations are Buddhist ought to implement specifics, but more theoretically about the kind of ideals a Buddhist, group of Buddhists, or Buddhist society might strive to achieve. Restorative justice encompasses a variety of ideas, perspectives, and methods (see Johnstone, 2003). As a general designator for an over-arching approach to criminal justice, I think quite a bit resonates with they type of approach Buddhists might want to take. The details of the shape it might one day take are the subject of lengthy and serious future considerations. I imagine that even within Buddhism or a Buddhist approach to these questions, the answers might take a variety of forms and context-specific adaptations depending on cultures, individuals, historical contexts, etc. Concluding Remarks Obviously these reflections here are merely preliminary. My aim is not so much to draw conclusions, as to open discussion. The primary point that I would like to make is not that Buddhists ought to Journal of Global Buddhism / 341 adopt a modification of Rawls' theory or that we identify ourselves as advocates of restorative justice (though I do think there are good arguments for the latter). I do not think that Buddhists necessarily need to fit their ideas into the structure – however modified – of philosophical positions alien to the tradition. Rather, my primary point, with the illustrations above, is that if we are going to engage in justice discourse at all, we ought to do it well. For when we use the term "justice," to some degree we already are attempting to fit into a philosophical category not entirely indigenous to Buddhism. Buddhists eager to take part in international dialog on social change, ought to begin a serious consideration of these sorts of philosophical topics, and we ought to equip ourselves to more fully engage in a global discourse on these philosophical and practical issues. It works to the benefit of the Buddhist tradition, moving forward as a global religion in the twenty-first century. When we isolate ourselves from a larger conversation, we deprive both ourselves and our potential conversation partners. (18 When Buddhists use technical terms from traditions of thought other than their own without clarity of its place in a larger philosophical dialog, it looks as if we are making ungrounded or unsubstantiated claims. Traditionally Buddhist philosophers did not isolate themselves from larger pan-Indian philosophical conversations, nor did they simply make unsubstantiated claims or assertions without considered reasoning behind them. For thinkers like Dignaaga and Dharmakiirti, ascent to scriptural authority is simply not sufficient. As we begin a new century and a new global Buddhism, it is imperative that Buddhists are able to articulate their views and converse with others on the world stage. If we are to have any meaningful impact in creating the sort of world we, as Engaged Buddhists, envision, then it must begin with a thorough and rigorous foundation. ) Notes 1. See for example Buddhadhasa Bhikkhu (1989) Sivaraksa (1992, 1999), Winer (2003) on Maha Ghosananda, Sangharakshita (1986) Journal of Global Buddhism / 342 and Blumenthal (1995) on Ambedkar, and His Holiness the Dalai Lama (2008). Dunne (1999) engages the topic with some technical terminology that is familiar to philosophers and religious studies scholars, though he does not engage in comparative work. King (2005) articulates Buddhist ideas about justice in some detail. See note 4, below. 2 . The philosophical foundations for Buddhist ideas on non-violence, responsibilities, and a host of other ethical issues have been treated extensively. See for example Sivaraksa (1992), Cabezón (1996), Nhat Hanh (1987, 1999), Harvey (2000), Samdong Rinpoche (2006), etc. 3. King (2005) begins the important work of articulating an Engaged Buddhist social ethics and ethical theory. In the process, she insightfully begins to address and analyze the questions of justice and social justice in the Engaged Buddhist context. She interviewed some leading thinkers from the movement, such as Sulak Sivaraksa and Samdong Rinpoche, on justice, and analyzes some important comments made by Geshe Sopa and Ven. Dhammananda in Israel concerning justice for Jews vis á vis the Holocaust and Israelis and Palestinians concerning their current conflict. All of this is an important contribution to a critical discussion, but it is largely carried out without reference to long history of philosophical discourse on justice from the Western canon from which the idea derives. 4. "Goods" is construed broadly here. It is not limited to material resources, but includes rights such as privacy, the right to vote, etc., legal constructs, access to "goods" such as education, medical care, etc. 5 . Christopher Queen (1996), drawing on theoretical insights developed by Clifford Geertz (1968), discusses the process by which Engaged Buddhists have engaged in a sort of "scripturalism" in returning to traditional and canonical texts and sources of religious authority, yet with innovative theological interpretations that render them newly relevant for contemporary circumstances, particularly in Journal of Global Buddhism / 343 times of perceived crisis. 6. Sulak Sivaraksa (1992: 103). Walpola Rahula (1985: 104) echoes this sentiment when he writes: "The Buddha did not take life out of the context of its social and economic background; he looked at it as a whole, in all its social, economic, and political aspects. His teaching on ethical, spiritual and philosophical problems are fairly well known. But little is known, particularly in the West, about his teaching on social, economic, and political matters. Yet there are numerous discourses dealing with these scattered throughout the ancient Buddhist texts." Others such as Samdong Rinpoche, Thich Nhat Hanh, His Holiness the Dalai Lama, and Buddhadasa exemplify this sentiment as they repeatedly turn to scriptural sources as evidence to support their Buddhist ideas about justice. 7. Gregory Schopen (1997) has persuasively argued for the use of non-textual sources in Buddhist Studies, particularly in attempting to historically decipher the contours of Buddhism on the ground in India in its earliest periods. There may well be good reason to make use of non-textual sources to help make some philosophical arguments regarding justice. However, my hunch is that sutta/sutra sources and philosophical treatises by early masters will probably prove to be more fruitful resources for this project since the explicit purpose is not a historical deciphering of ancient Buddhism on the ground. 8. Any discussion of the just distribution of goods will also entail implications for issues in criminal justice as well. This will be discussed further in the following section. 9. Some scholars and thinkers within the traditions have argued the opposite, that the contemporary Engaged Buddhist movements represent a dramatic shift in Buddhist thinking. See for example Queen (1996: 1-44, 2000: 1-29), the discussion of Joanna Macy in Kaza (2000 160), and Litsch (2000: 423). Perhaps the clearest example of this side of the question of whether Buddhism has always had an engaged component or whether it is a new innovation Journal of Global Buddhism / 344 (both recent and highly influenced by Buddhism's recent encounters with the West) is summarized by Christopher Queen (2000: 1-2) when he writes in his, "Introduction: A New Buddhism," that, "I shall argue that the general pattern of belief and practice that has come to be called 'engaged Buddhism' is unprecedented, and thus tantamount to a new chapter in the history of the tradition. As a style of ethical practice, engaged Buddhism may be seen as a new paradigm of Buddhist liberation. Invoking traditional terminology, Buddhists might call it a "new vehicle" – or Navayana… - or a fourth yana in the evolution of the dharma." Thomas Yarnall (2003) summarizes and critically analyzes both sides of this debate, while infusing a degree of theoretical sophistication that has been lacking in much engaged Buddhist scholarship. Among the many insights found in his analysis, Yarnall, while recognizing important contributions made in Queen's argument that Engaged Buddhism fundamentally constitutes a new vehicle (yana) of Buddhim, he criticizes the modernist and orientalist tendencies he finds in the perspective of Queen and like-minded thinkers. 10. See for example Hanh (1987), Sivaraksa (1992), Gyatso (1999a and 2008), etc. 11 . The four brahmavihaaras are loving-kindness, compassion, sympathetic joy, and equanimity. See Buddhaghosa. Visuddhimagga (The Path of Purification). Pp. 288-319. 12. See for example, Tsongkhapa. Byang chub lam rim chen mo (The Great Treatise on the Stages of the Path to Enlightenment). 13. Kamala"siila. Bhaavanaakrama II.4. de la snying rje bsgom pa'i rim pa de dang po 'jug pa nas brtsams te brjod par bya'o/ thog mar re zhig btang snyoms bsgoms pas sems can thams cad la rjes su chags pa dang/ khong khro ba bsal te snyoms pa'i sems nyid bsgrub par bya'o/ sems can thams cad bde ba ni 'dod sdug bsngal ba ni mi 'dod la/ thog ma med pa can gyi 'khor ban a sems can gang lan brgyar dag gi gnyen du ma gyur pa de gang yang med do snyam du yongs su bsam zhing// 'di la byed brag ci zhig yod na la la la ni rjes su chags/ la la la ni khong khro bar gyur bas/ de lta bas na bdag gis sems can Journal of Global Buddhism / 345 thams cad la sems snyoms pa nyid du bya'o snyam du de ltar yid la bya zhing bar ma'i phyogs nas brtsams te/ mdza' bshes dang dgra la yang sems snyoms pa nyid du bsgom mo/ 14 . Truth and Reconcilliation Commission homepage, http://www.doj.gov.za/trc/ 6/1/2009. 15. One such unique contribution that immediately comes to mind is the success of the Vipassana retreats held in prisons by S.N. Goenke. For an excellent documentary on this, see Menahemi and Ariel (1997). 16. The specifics of what shape such a reform-oriented prison would take is, of course, an enormous topic that is outside of the scope of this paper. 17. Ideally it would not require an explicit "Buddhist" influence on the state. By participating in a global conversation, Buddhists can have an impact without an exceedingly imposing use of Buddhist language. The Dalai Lama is quite skillful at this in his recent book, Ethics for the New Millenium, which discusses his views on ethics in purely secular language. 18. This isolationism has been a longstanding problem of Buddhist Studies within the larger disciplines of Religious Studies and Philosophy. Those working in Buddhist epistemology and logic have made great strides in this regard in the past ten to fifteen years. Cited Sources BLUMENTHAL, JAMES (1995) "Buddhism Among India's Ex-Untouchables: Implications of Conversion and the Use of Buddhist Ideology as a Model for Social Justice". M.A. Thesis, University of Wisconsin – Madison. BUDDHADHASA BHIKKHU (1989) Me and Mine: Selected Essays of Bhikkhu Buddhadasa. Trans. Donald K. Swearer. Albany: State University of New York Press. http://www.doj.gov.za/trc/� Journal of Global Buddhism / 346 BUDDHAGHOSA, BHADANTACARIYA (trans. Bhikkhu ~Naamoli ) (1991 edition). The Path of Purification (Visuddhimagga). Seattle: BPS Pariyati Editions. CABEZÓN, JOSÉ (1996). "Buddhist Principles in the Tibetan Liberation Movement". Pp. 295-320. In C. Queen and S. King (eds.) Engaged Buddhism: Buddhist Liberation Movements in Asia. Albany: State University of New York Press. CHAPPELL, DAVID (Ed.) (1999) Buddhist Peacework: Creating Cultures of Peace. Boston: Wisdom Publications. DUNNE, JOHN D (2000). "On Essences, Goals, and Social Justice: An Exercise in Buddhist Theology." Pp. 275-292. In R. Jackson and J. Makransky (eds.) Buddhist Theology: Critical Reflections by Contemporary Buddhist Scholars. London: Curzon Press. GEERTZ, CLIFFORD (1968) Islam Observed: Religious Development in Morocco and Indonesia. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. GYATSO, TENZIN (DALAI LAMA XIV) (1999a). "Dialogue on Religion and Peace". Pp. 189-198 in D.W. Chappell (ed.) In Buddhist Peacework: Creating Cultures of Peace. Boston: Wisdom Publications. ———(1999b). Ethics For a New Millennium. New York: Penguin Putnam. ——— (2008). "Public Lectures on Santideva's Guide to the Bodhisattva's Way of Life and Kamalala's Stages of Meditation". Madison, WI. July 18-24, 2008. HADLEY, MICHAEL L. (Ed.) (2001) The Spiritual Roots of Restorative Justice. Albany: State University of New York Press. HARVEY, PETER (2000) Introduction to Buddhist Ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Journal of Global Buddhism / 347 JOHNSTONE, JERRY (Ed.) (2003) A Restorative Justice Reader: Texts, Sources, and Context. Portland: Willan Publishing. KAMALA"SIILA. BHAAVANAAKRAMA (bsGom pa'i rim bar pa, [Middle] Stages of Meditation). P5311, Vol. 102. KAZA, STEPHANIE (2000) "To Save All Beings: Buddhist Environmental Activism". Pp.159-183 in Christopher Queen (ed.) Engaged Buddhism in the West. Boston: Wisdom Publications. KING, SALLY (2005) Being Benevolence: The Social Ethics of Engaged Buddhism. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press. LITSCH, FRANZ-JOHANNES (2000) "Engaged Buddhism in German-Speaking Europe." Pp. 423-445 in Christopher Queen (ed.) Engaged Buddhism in the West. Boston: Wisdom Publications. LOY, DAVID R. (2001). "Healing Justice: A Buddhist Perspective". Pp. 81-98 in M.L. Hadley (ed.) The Spiritual Roots of Restorative Justice. Albany: State University of New York Press. MENAHEMI, AYLET & EILONA ARIEL (Producers and Directors) (1997) Doing Time, Doing Vipassana (Dharma Giri, India: Vipassana Research Institute). ~NAAMOLI, BHIKKHU & BHIKKHU BODHI (Trans.) (1995) The Middle Discourses of the Buddha: A Translation of the Majjhima Nikaaya. Boston: Wisdom Publications. NHAT HANH (1987) Interbeing: Fourteen Guidelines for Engaged Buddhism. Berkeley: Parallax Press. ——— (1999) "Ahimsa: The Path of Harmlessness". Pp. 155-164. In D. Chappell (Ed.) Buddhist Peacework: Creating Cultures of Peace. Boston: Wisdom Publications. QUEEN, CHRISTOPHER (1996) "Introduction: The Shapes and Sources of Engaged Buddhism" Pp. 1-44 in Queen, Christopher and Journal of Global Buddhism / 348 Sally King (eds.). Engaged Buddhism: Buddhist Liberation Movements in Asia. Albany: State University of New York Press. ——— (2000) "Introduction: A New Buddhism" Pp. 1-33. In Queen, Christopher (ed.). Engaged Buddhism in the West. Boston: Wisdom Publications. QUEEN, CHRISTOPHER, CHARLES PREBISH, & DAMIEN KEOWN (eds.). (2003) Action Dharma: New Studies in Engaged Buddhism. London: RoutledgeCurzon. RAHULA, WALPOLA (1985) "The Social Teachings of the Buddha". Pp. 103-110. In F. Eppsteiner (Ed.) The Path of Compassion: Writings on Socially Engaged Buddhism. Berkeley: Parallax Press. RAWLS, JOHN (1971, 1999 revised edition). A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. ——— (2001) Justice as Fairness: A Restatement. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. SAMDHONG RINPOCHE (2006) Uncompromising Truth for a Compromised World: Tibetan Buddhism and Today's World. Bloomington: World Wisdom Inc. SANGHARAKSHITA (1986). Ambedkar and Buddhism. Glasgow: Windhorse Publications. SCHOPEN, GREGORY (1997). "Archeology and Protestant Presuppositions in the Study of Indian Buddhism". Pp. 1-22. In G. Schopen. Bones, Stones, and Buddhist Monks: Collected Papers on the Archaeology, Epigraphy, and Texts of Monastic Buddhism in India. Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press. SIVARAKSA, SULAK (1992) Seeds of Peace: A Buddhist Vision for Renewing Society. Berkeley: Parallax Press. ——— (1999) "Buddhism and a Culture of Peace." Pp. 39-46 in D. Chappell (Ed.) Buddhist Peacework: Creating Cultures of Peace. Journal of Global Buddhism / 349 Boston: Wisdom Publications. THURMAN, ROBERT A. F. (1985) "Nagarjuna's Guidelines for Buddhist Social Action." Pp. 120-144 in F. Eppsteiner (Ed.) The Path of Compassion: Writings on Socially Engaged Buddhism. Berkeley: Parallax Press. Truth and Reconcilliation Commission homepage [internet]. Available from http://www.doj.gov.za/trc/ [accessed June 5, 2009] TSONG-KHA-PA. Byang chub lam rim chen mo (Great Treatise on the Stage of the Path to Enlightenment). P6001, Vol. 152. VASUBHANDHU (1923, 1931) ABHIDHARMKO"SABHAA"SYA (Chos mngon paiI mdzod kyi bshad pa). P5591. Vol. 104. Translation by Louis de La Vallée Poussin, L"Abhidharmakoßa de Vasubandhu. Paris: Geunther.. WEINER, MATHEW (2003) "Maha Ghosananda as a Contemplative Social Activist." Pp. 110-125 in C. Queen, C. Prebish, and D. Keown (eds.) Action Dharma: New Studies in Engaged Buddhism. London: RoutledgeCurzon. YARNALL, THOMAS FREEMAN (2003), “Engaged Buddhism: New or Improved? Made in the USA of Asian Materials.” Pp. 286-344 in C. Queen, C. Prebish, and D. (eds.), Action Dharma: New Studies in Engaged Buddhism. London: RoutledgeCurzon. http://www.doj.gov.za/trc/� work_4oqwvjzxr5f5zkyl3prdrb6mai ---- Defending the State, Defending the Religion 115 JOURNAL OF INDONESIAN ISLAM Volume 13, Number 01, June 2019 SECURING THE STATE, DEFENDING THE RELIGION An Analysis of Boelan Sabit Newspaper Publications (December 1945-January 1946) Muhammad Yuanda Zara Yogyakarta State University – Indonesia | m.yuanda@uny.ac.id Abstract: This article discusses how the narration of Islamic- ness and Indonesian-ness in the midst of the war of independence was represented in an Islamic newspaper called Boelan Sabit. The period under study is a month (December 15, 1945-January 14, 1946). Using the historical method, the research findings revealed that Boelan Sabit newspaper incessantly called for Indonesian Muslims to defend Indonesian independence from Dutch colonialism and British occupation based on both Islam and nationalism. The newspaper ensured its Muslim readers that the period of independence was a time to strengthen the two identities inherent in them, namely a son of Indonesia and a Muslim. In this regard, this newspaper took the legitimacy and inspiration in maintaining Indonesian independence from the Quran and other resources of Islamic teachings. In addition, Boelan Sabit newspaper encouraged Muslim readers to have broad knowledge concerning on affairs of state through publishing articles about modern state-related concepts, including deliberation, sovereignty, democracy, and dominion status. Further, this newspaper had a role in helping Indonesian Muslims to understand and accept their new identity after the second world war as a patriotic Indonesian citizen as well as a pious Muslim. Keywords: Islam, nationalism, Indonesian war of independence, Islamic press. Introduction Until the arrival of Japanese troops in Indonesia in 1942, the majority of Indonesian Muslims were almost politically inactive and socio-economically weak. Most of them lived in rural areas, were DOI: 10.15642/JIIS.2019.13.1.115-140 mailto:m.yuanda@uny.ac.id Muhammad Yuanda Zara JOURNAL OF INDONESIAN ISLAM Volume 13, Number 01, June 2019 116 illiterate, and apolitical. However, in the last months of 1945, the Indonesian Muslims changed dramatically. Indonesian Muslim leaders worked together with their nationalist compatriots to proclaim Indonesian independence and managed this newborn country. Muslim youth joined both the national army and paramilitary organizations to fight the Dutch, who wished to resume their colonialism in Indonesia, and the British, who claimed to come to Indonesia to disarm Japanese troops. They were even willing to sacrifice themselves by fighting against more trained British and Dutch forces. How can Indonesian Muslims become one of the strongest backbones in the struggle of the Republic of Indonesia against the Dutch and the British? Newspapers play an important role in times of conflict. Newspapers are one of the mass communication media used by belligerents to influence the public, seek support, increase morale, and weaken the enemy. These aims are possible to reach through newspapers given newspapers’ wide reach, moving rhetoric written by experienced journalists or writers, and touching photographs. In newspapers war is imagined, represented and disseminated. Newspapers help shaping public attitude towards war, either supporting or rejecting it. In other words, as stated by Glenn R. Wilkinson, public attitudes made war possible.1 Therefore, in order to study the public attitude towards war, a study of how war is represented in public space is needed, including in the print media. Roy Morris Jr., in his introduction to a book about print media and Civil War in America, underlined that newspapers and magazines have played a role in bringing conflict and war into the living rooms and parlors of (American) public, which in turn means that the power of the press is increasingly solidified and expanded.2 This holds true in Indonesian case during the war of independence, which lasted from 1945-1949. Through the print media the war reached the hands of ordinary Indonesians. Therefore, understanding the struggle for Indonesian independence will not complete without comprehending how Muslims thought and voiced their support for the Republic 1 Glenn R. Wilkinson, Depictions and images of war in Edwardian newspapers, 1899-1914 (Hampshire and New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2003), p. 1. 2 Roy Morris, Jr., “Introduction,” David B. Sachsman, S. Kittrell Rushing, and Roy Morris Jr. (eds), Words at war: The Civil War and American Journalism (Indiana: Purdue University Press, 2008), p. 9. Defending the State, Defending the Religion 117 JOURNAL OF INDONESIAN ISLAM Volume 13, Number 01, June 2019 through various kinds of media, with one of the most important being newspapers. The literature on the role of nationalist newspapers in Indonesia during the Dutch-Indonesian conflict (1945-1949) has been written quite a lot.3 However, Islamic journalism in this time of conflict received very little attention from historians. This paper is the first study that systematically examines the workings of Islamic press, especially Boelan Sabit, during the war of independence in Indonesia. This study provides a perspective on how an Islamic newspaper played a role in the midst of one of the bloodiest conflicts after the Second World War. Boelan Sabit openly supported the Republic of Indonesia and rejected the presence of the Dutch and the British. Given that its readers were educated Indonesian Muslims, this newspaper justified its pro-Republic stance both by patriotic and Islamic arguments. This newspaper helped shaping the public perception among Indonesian Muslims, that at that time Indonesian Muslims had to adopt a new position: devout Muslims as well as patriotic sons of Indonesia, who had to defend their independence from foreign invasion, if necessary with their lives. This paper examines how the narration of Islamic-ness and Indonesian-ness in the midst of the conflict was represented in an Islamic newspaper. The newspaper examined in this study was Boelan Sabit (literally means ‘crescent’, often associated as the symbol of Islam), which was published by the Indonesian Islamic Youth Movement (Gerakan Pemoeda Islam Indonesia, GPII), a youth wing of an Islamic party that was founded in 7 November 1945, Masyumi4. 3 For example, see Andi Suwirta’s study on Jakarta-based newspaper, Merdeka, and Yogyakarta-based newspaper, Kedaulatan Rakjat, during the Dutch-Indonesian conflict, Suara dari Dua Kota: Revolusi Indonesia dalam Pandangan Surat Kabar “Merdeka” (Jakarta) dan “Kedaulatan Rakjat” (Yogyakarta) 1945-1947 (Jakarta: Balai Pustaka, 2000). See also J.R. Chaniago, et. al., Ditugaskan Sejarah: Perjuangan Merdeka, 1945-1985 (Jakarta: Pustaka Merdeka, 1987); David T. Hill, Journalism and Politics in Indonesia: A Critical Biography of Mochtar Lubis (1922-2004) as Editor and Author (Oxon & New York: Routledge, 2010) especially Part II Chapter 3, ‘The “press of political struggle”: the first Indonesia Raya’, and Muhammad Yuanda Zara, “‘Trust Me, This News is Indeed True’: Representations of Violence in Indonesian Newspapers during the Indonesian Revolution, 1945-1948,” Bart Luttikhuis & A. Dirk Moses (eds), Colonial Counterinsurgency and Mass Violence: The Dutch Empire in Indonesia (Oxon & New York: Routledge, 2014). 4 The Masyumi party was very influential in Indonesia and had a very broad mass base. One of its founders, Mohammad Natsir, was appointed Republican Minister of Muhammad Yuanda Zara JOURNAL OF INDONESIAN ISLAM Volume 13, Number 01, June 2019 118 In this regard, this paper investigates news, opinions and poems related to Islam and Indonesia published by this newspaper. The period examined in this article is between 15 December 1945 and 14 January 1946. There are several reasons for the selection of this period. First, this one month period is a crucial period for the Republic of Indonesia. About a month earlier, fighting broke out between Indonesian freedom fighters and British forces in Surabaya, the second largest city in Indonesia. This battle continued until the following months and, most importantly, sparked a strongly negative sentiment among the Indonesian people towards the British presence. In the period between December 1945 and January 1946, both the British and the Dutch were able to strengthen their foothold in Java and Sumatra. As a result, in early January 1946 the Republican government moved its capital from Jakarta (which was occupied by the Dutch and the British) to Yogyakarta in the interior of Java. The second reason is practical. The 15 December 1945 edition was the earliest edition of Boelan Sabit available in the National Library of the Republic of Indonesia in Jakarta. The period of one month is representative enough to understand about the aspects of Islam and Indonesia during the conflict.5 By using historical method, the purpose of this study is to find out how ideas about Islam and Indonesia were envisioned, expressed and disseminated by the Islamic press following the birth of the Republic of Indonesia and the coming of the British and the Dutch. How did Boelan Sabit view Indonesia’s independence and the arrival of the British and the Dutch troops to Indonesia? How did Boelan Sabit perceive the position of Muslims in the newly born Republic of Indonesia? How were arguments originating from Islamic teachings used as a justification to support Indonesia as well as to fight against foreign forces? Information as of January 3, 1946. This Party was founded on 7 November 1945, and was the only party in Indonesia that represented Islamic ideology at least until the next two years. See Rémy Madinier, Islam and Politics in Indonesia: The Masyumi Party between Democracy and Integralism (Singapore: NUS Press, 2015), pp. 76-77. 5 Boelan Sabit was published in Indonesian. The English translation in this paper is mine. Defending the State, Defending the Religion 119 JOURNAL OF INDONESIAN ISLAM Volume 13, Number 01, June 2019 Spiritualizing Indonesian Independence Boelan Sabit newspaper strongly supported Indonesian independence and was against the presence of the Dutch and the British forces. Even when it discussed Islamic teachings, it contextualized the discussion within the framework of Indonesian independence. For example, when Boelan Sabit in a full front page discussed about the 10 Muharram as the Ashura Day On 15 December 1945 (10 Muharram 1365 H). Although the headlines of the day discussed important days in Islamic history, the article itself was opened not only with ‘bismilla>h’ (in the name of Allah) but also with a reminder of the new age that Indonesian Muslims were entering: “Thank to God who has helped us encountering the new age, the Age of Independence of Indonesian Land.” 6 This statement clearly confirmed the position of Boelan Sabit as supporters of the Republic of Indonesia and its self-proclaimed independence. Futher, the Islamic element was clearly present in Boelan Sabit’s efforts to strengthen its appeal to Muslims in Central Java to support the Republic of Indonesia. Boelan Sabit emphasized the principles of the Masyumi Party in its effort to show its inclination both for supporting the Republic and the role of Islam in the newborn state. In the 14 January 1946 edition of Boelan Sabit, for example, it was confirmed by Boelan Sabit’s editorial that the Masyumi principle was twofold, namely “Upholding the sovereignty of the Republic of Indonesia and the Islamic Religion” and “Implementing Islamic ideals in Indonesian state affairs”.7 Occasionally, when calling Indonesian Muslims to defend Indonesia’s independence Boelan Sabit used stories of glorious Islamic past. Long time ago, wrote a journalist from Boelan Sabit in his article, ‘Menoedjoe djalan kebahagiaan’ (Towards the path of happiness), 14 January 1946, Muslims had achieved highest glory; they even became teachers for the rest of the world. However, then they became ungrateful for God’s favor and were busy pursuing worldly pleasures. As a result, internal disputes arose and led to bloodshed and schism. Muslims fell from glory to destruction. It was only in the 20th century that Muslims regained their consciousness. The same held true for Indonesia, which could be seen from various kinds of Islamic 6 “Sepoeloeh Moeharom (‘Asjoero),” Boelan Sabit, 15 December 1945. 7 “Haloean kita: “Kedaulatan Rakjat,” Boelan Sabit, 14 January 1946. Muhammad Yuanda Zara JOURNAL OF INDONESIAN ISLAM Volume 13, Number 01, June 2019 120 movements aimed at elevating the degree of Indonesian Muslims since the beginning of the 20th century. The peak of this effort was the independence of Indonesia and the establishment of the Republic of Indonesia since 1945.8 And, according to Boelan Sabit, Muslims were obliged to maintain such independence: We are from the side of the Muslim Ummah: we are in full confidence with our 100 percent independence, and there is no better time for us than now, when we must attempt to maintain the perpetuity of our independence, and with the help God it must succeed. An Arabic proverb says: “If the crescent moon appears, it is clear for us that the full moon will come”.9 Boelan Sabit supported the Republican government’s position that Indonesia was already independent and that the Republic of Indonesia was a legitimate government. This newspaper rejected the views of the Dutch and the British that the Republic of Indonesia had no legitimacy to act as a state. War was the last resort if Indonesia’s aspirations for independence were hindered. In the last week of December 1945, news were circulated in Indonesia that the Dutch and the British would hold a conference in London, where they would discuss the matter concerning the returning of Dutch rule in Indonesia. Masyumi, through his Head Office (Pengurus Besar), represented by Abi Koesno Tjokrosoejoso, criticized the plan for this meeting. His criticism, which was published in Boelan Sabit on 26 December 1945, emphasized the fact that Indonesia was not invited to the conference, which indicated that Indonesia was not considered as an independent country. In other words, Indonesia had not been recognized internationally. Meanwhile, in Indonesia the Dutch and British troops continued to commit acts of violence which provoked strong resistance from Indonesian Muslims. If this continued, Masyumi Head Office instructed Muslims to prepare for a holy war against the Dutch and the British. “Wait for the call for Sabil war [perang Sabil]”, Masyumi Head Office commanded the party’s followers.10 By using the term 'perang Sabil’, which can be translated as ‘to fight for the cause of God’, Masyumi and Boelan Sabit were actually 8 “Menoedjoe djalan kebahagiaan,” Boelan Sabit, 14 January 1946. 9 Ibid. 10 “Moe’tamar GPII di kota Bengawan,” Boelan Sabit, 26 December 1945. Defending the State, Defending the Religion 121 JOURNAL OF INDONESIAN ISLAM Volume 13, Number 01, June 2019 campaigning that the reasons to resist the Dutch and the British were not solely nationalism and anti-colonialism. There was a higher, if not the highest, reason for Muslims, which was related to human-divine connections: fighting the enemy because of following God’s orders. Further, it is interesting to note that the efforts to reject the presence of the Dutch and the British, Boelan Sabit took Islam as the legitimacy to support the Republic of Indonesia. The source of their legitimacy came from the main and highest source of Islamic teachings: the Quran. In 15 December 1945 edition, the journalist of Boelan Sabit, in the “Roeangan Tafsir” (Interpretation of Quran) column, interpreted the 85th surah in the Quran, Surah Al Buruj (‘The Big Stars’). This surah talks about the Islamic faith, the power of Allah over the earth and the sky, and the sacrifice of those who believe in Allah and about those who reject Allah’s commands, for what they will be punished by Allah. In other words, in this last part, Allah divides people into two groups. First, believers, or those who follow Allah’s commands, and those who disobey, those who reject Allah’s commands. It was implied from Boelan Sabit interpretation that the British and Dutch colonizers were classified as those who were against Allah’s command: The godless people boast and puff up their chest against the truth and justice that God loves. The Indonesian people will continue to fight every colonial tyranny. Even though the British and the Dutch had made a decision (at the Singapore conference), they will commit acts of violence against Indonesia, [but] they will be stabbed by their own weapons, and they will accept God’s torment inside the extremey hot hell. 11 Journalist of Boelan Sabit also ensured its readers that the colonizers would be chased by “defenders of truth and justice”. The journalist claimed a few examples from abroad where the native people were fighting against the domination of the foreign invaders, such as in Annam (Vietnam), India and Africa.12 Boelan Sabit advocated the amalgamation between nationalism and religion within an Indonesian. One of its reports in 15 December 1945 read as follows: From the conscious sons and daughters of Nusantara, born a spirit of life, a national spirit which is usually inherited by the 11 “Sepoeloeh Moeharom (‘Asjoero),” Boelan Sabit, 15 December 1945. 12 Ibid. Muhammad Yuanda Zara JOURNAL OF INDONESIAN ISLAM Volume 13, Number 01, June 2019 122 nations of the world. From their mouths came the recognition of “TRILOGY”. One nation: Indonesia. One Indonesian country. One Indonesian language. Apart from that, for those who are aware, with true Religion the world community will be safe in its broadest meaning of the word. So, we have also yelled [that we are the adherents of the] “RELIGION OF ISLAM”.13 In addition, the editor of Boelan Sabit interpreted the 84th surah in Al-Qur'an, Al-Insyiqaq (‘To Split Asunder’) in the context of the struggle for maintaining Indonesian independence. This surah tells about the fate of humans on the Day of Judgment. Some get happiness and return to their Lord in a happy state. But some return in a sad state. Who gets happiness? They, according to the journalist of Boelan Sabit, were those who understood that life was not only in this world but also in the hereafter. This awareness, the journalist continued, led them “to be wise to use their lives for things that are more beneficial for the nation, homeland and religion.”14 These people were “those who are named believers and those who are willing to sacrifice”. Islam was described as the source of inspiration for resistance against the foreign invaders. An article by the journalist of Boelan Sabit (name unknown), entitled “Revolusi dan Islam” (Revolution and Islam), was published in the newspaper in 26 December 1945. In the beginning, the author questioned, what was the source of strength that “was capable of throwing enemies into the sea”? The answer, said the author, was “the basis of Islam”. This was the basis that must be used in the revolutionary struggle of the homeland. He continued that the enemy had brought difficulties to the Indonesian people intending to weaken the enthusiasm of the people. Based on Islam, the writer continued, Muslims will realize that this troubled world was not the end, but only an arena where a Muslim was tested and must pass an examination. Therefore, “however severe suffering is, it will only be lightly felt in the hearts of every Muslim”.15 He continued: So, “with Islam”, the people will be big-spirited. And, with Islam the revolution can continue. For Muslims, the spirit of “sabilillah” [in the way of Allah] is the realization of a great soul. Then, all 13 “Menebalkan semangat tjinta bangsa,” Boelan Sabit, 15 December 1945. 14 “Soerat Insjiqoq,” Boelan Sabit, 26 December 1945. 15 “Revolusi dan Islam,” Boelan Sabit, 26 December 1945. Defending the State, Defending the Religion 123 JOURNAL OF INDONESIAN ISLAM Volume 13, Number 01, June 2019 Indonesian people must have it to continue their revolution. To find out the greatness of the soul of Islam, we only need to present half of the teachings of Islam which comprises the spirit of revolution: Who dies but has never fought, and in his heart there is no willingness to fight, he dies as a hypocrite. 16 In a conference on 26-27 December 1945 in the Habiprojo Building in Surakarta, the GPII praised two paramilitary groups affiliated to Masyumi, Sabilillah and Hizboelloh, in their efforts to fight the foreign invaders. Boelan Sabit made the news of this conference the main news in the 29 December 1945 edition. By quoting the results of the meeting, the Boelan Sabit journalist wrote that Sabilillah and Hizboelloh were “atomic [bombs] that destroyed enemies and spies”.17 The term “Atomic [bombs]” (“Atoom” in original text) here clearly brought readers to recall the enormity of the power of the atomic bombs dropped by the United States on Hiroshima and Nagasaki, Japan, less than six months earlier. The atomic bombs destroyed two cities in Japan, and made Japan, which for the previous several years was very powerful, surrendered to the United States and finally ended the Second World War. Comparing American atomic bombs with Sabilillah and Hizboelloh as atomic bombs which destroyed the enemy was clearly an effort to strengthen enthusiasm to the members of these two groups and to show how dangerous they were in front of the enemy. Besides, “Atoom” in this article also had other meaning. The chairman of the meeting, Harjono, interpreted this term differently. For him, “Atoom” stood for “Alloh Tolong Orang-orang Moeslimin” (Allah helps Muslims).18 Interestingly, GPII, and Boelan Sabit as its spokesperson believed that the struggle should not only be carried out by male youth. Although women were not expected to take up arms, they also had an equally important role. Regarding the role of Muslim women at war, in the late December 1945 meeting, as reported by Boelan Sabit, a female envoy from the GPII women’s section, Hidanah, stressed that Muslim women in times of turbulence had three types of obligations, namely obligations to themselves, obligations to household and obligations to 16 “Revolusi dan Islam”. 17 “Rapat oemoem moe’tamar GPII,” Boelan Sabit, 29 December 1945. 18 Ibid. Muhammad Yuanda Zara JOURNAL OF INDONESIAN ISLAM Volume 13, Number 01, June 2019 124 community. 19 To themselves, they were obliged to educate themselves, while for households, they were obliged to manage the household well. As for the community, they were obliged to realize the noble ideals of mothers. Equally important, Hidanah underlined that without mothers there would be no men and youth fighters. In the meeting, Hidanah asked rhetorically: “Who gave birth to the Prophet Muhammad? Who gave birth to Prince Diponegoro? Who gave birth to the heroes who are now marching to the front line? Women, right? Then, pay respect to women!”20 In addition to publishing views that motivate its readers to fight the Dutch and the British, Boelan Sabit also released news about the Indonesian people’s resistance against the foreign invaders in a very pro-Indonesia tone. Boelan Sabit had confirmed its pro-Republican attitude since the beginning, thus it is understandable when its reports clearly supported Indonesian independence and anti-colonialism attitude. Educating Muslims about Politics Boelan Sabit did not only report violence and fighting involving Muslim youth. For this newspaper, fighting was an important way to defend the sovereignty of the Republic from the Dutch and British hindrance. However, there was another important task to do, namely to expand the knowledge and understanding of the readers, most of whom were educated Muslims, regarding basic concepts of statehood. The aim was to ensure that Muslims were not just preoccupied with fighting the enemy in the battlefield, but also to increase knowledge and skills in managing the newly born country. Muslims were the biggest part of Indonesian society, so they were expected to participate in running the state. The GPII itself, as the mother organization of Boelan Sabit, in its Articles of Association (Anggaran Dasar), especially in Article 6 (Efforts), did not only emphasize how they seek to deepen Islamic knowledge (point A) and the application of these teachings among its members (point B), but also had an effort to “Enhance intelligence and skill of Islamic youth in state matters” (point C).21 19 Ibid. 20 Ibid. 21 “Anggaran Dasar Gerakan Pemoeda Islam Indonesia,” Boelan Sabit, 29 December 1945. Defending the State, Defending the Religion 125 JOURNAL OF INDONESIAN ISLAM Volume 13, Number 01, June 2019 A method to do this was by providing various columns that contained knowledge about democracy, sovereignty of the people, and state administration. Boelan Sabit introduced concepts relating to modern state. These concepts were discussed in the Roeangan Pengetahoean Politik (Political Knowledge) column, which was presented serially. One of them was the definition and explanation of the principle of “musyawarah” (deliberation) which was the main notion of the fourth principle in the Pancasila (Indonesian state principle of five pillars). Deliberation, according to the author who discussed it in Boelan Sabit, was a method to make decisions. However, the majority did not necessarily the one who held the truth. Therefore, two steps were necessary; first, adopting deliberation as a method to make a decision, and second, educating the people to be more intelligent, which in turn would make them increasingly responsible for managing common issues. 22 Another issue discussed by Boelan Sabit was on the form of government in postwar Indonesia. The discussion was sourced from government and Islamic leaders, or was taken from other media outlets that specialized in state matters. One example can be seen in Knowledge and Politics column in the 2 January 1946 edition of Boelan Sabit. An article was published, entitled “’Dominion Status’ Arti dan Isinja” (‘Dominion Status’: Its Meaning and Contents). This was taken from the Pantja Raja magazine. 23 Interestingly, there was no other reason to publish this article than to reject the contents. At the beginning of this article, the editorial staff of Boelan Sabit wrote: “In order to broaden the knowledge concerning politics, here we publish ‘Dominion Status’, and we hope it is not to be swallowed up! We only want independence 100 pCt.”24 The dominion status discussed here was linked to the history of two nations that have long fought for independence, namely India and Indonesia. In the beginning, more space was given to the discussion of the presence of dominion status as one of the demands of the Indian nationalists to the British rule. The All India Congress since 1885 requested self-government for India. The request changed into a Home Rule, and finally, since 1916, a dominion status. This demand 22 “Demokrasi,” Boelan Sabit, 15 December 1945. 23 “Roeangan Pengetahoean dan Politik: ‘Dominion Status’, Arti dan Isinja,” Boelan Sabit, 2 January 1946. 24 Ibid. Muhammad Yuanda Zara JOURNAL OF INDONESIAN ISLAM Volume 13, Number 01, June 2019 126 failed because of British refusal to fulfill it. As for Indonesia, according to this article, dominion status for Indonesia had been echoed by Indonesian nationalists since 1936 when Soetardjo, an Indonesian member of Dutch-created representative body, petitioned about dominion status at the Dutch East Indies People’s Council. Four years later, another Indonesian nationalist, Wiwoho, also recommended dominion status before the People’s Council session. Some other nationalists put forward the same demand in 1940 to the Visman Commission, a commission established by the colonial government to investigate aspirations of the native.25 Furthermore, the author of the article asserted that dominion status was the Dutch proposal as a solution to the post-Second World War political problems in Indonesia. The Dutch gave the Indonesian people authority to regulate their country, but they were still under the Kingdom of the Netherlands. This status referred to the example used by the British Empire, namely its dominion areas outside the United Kingdom which were controlled by British and other Westerners, encompassing Canada, New Foundland, South Africa, Australia, New Zealand and Ireland.26 An example like this was what Indonesian people imagined would be applied by the Dutch in Indonesia. Although Indonesian nationalists had proposed a dominion status for about a decade before, but it was clear that Boelan Sabit rejected this option. Its demands were full independence and sovereignty, and without the need to be under the Kingdom of the Netherlands. For Boelan Sabit, the one and only authority in Indonesia was the Republic of Indonesia, led by President Soekarno and Vice President Mohammad Hatta. Their orders must be carried out, and not orders from the Dutch or the British. Boelan Sabit passed on to his readers various instructions from President Soekarno. It thus acted as government spokesman. Two important things emphasized by Soekarno in the era of maintaining independence were the so-called coordination and consolidation. Boelan Sabit even made this theme the main news on 7 January 1946 under the heading “Haloean Kita: Koordinasi-Konsolidasi” (Our Direction: Coordination-Consolidation). The meaning of coordination, according to the author, was the close relationship between various struggle bodies and ideological schools, 25 Ibid. 26 “Roeangan Pengetahoean dan Politik: ‘Dominion Status’, Arti dan Isinja,” article 2, Boelan Sabit, 7 January 1946. Defending the State, Defending the Religion 127 JOURNAL OF INDONESIAN ISLAM Volume 13, Number 01, June 2019 while consolidation referred to efforts to harmonize the movements between various struggle organizations.27 The Boelan Sabit editorial elaborated on what Indonesian people and especially Muslims must do in the war situation. First, it ensured that the source of the struggle for Muslims was Islam, from which came the noble attitudes such as honesty, sincerity, purity, discipline, and obedience and fear of God. These virtues would create a close unity which cannot be divided. Besides being guided by President Soekarno’s advice on coordination and consolidation, there were two other efforts that must be performed especially by Indonesian Muslims, namely: (1) defending our independence from the invaders, by fighting through the way of the army, (2) upholding and regulating order in our country, implementing the arrangement of the government, by giving efforts in state administration. 28 In addition, the editorial staff of Boelan Sabit emphasized several directions that Indonesian Muslims must understand. First, both diplomacy and military were equally important, and both must be carried out together. Secondly, the struggle body and political parties should be rooted in the will of the people. Third, the government had established a centralized military effort under the command of the TKR (People’s Security Army) while the political body and ideologies centered on the Komite Nasional Indonesia (KNI, Indonesian National Committee). Finally, the group selfishness must be diminished given that selfishness may spark hazardous competition for power, jealousy, and mutual defamation that may make “our enemies laugh, because we are easily weakened”.29 On 6 and 7 January 1946, Masyumi held a ‘koersoes kilat’ (quick- brief course). In this course, rather than military tactics and weapons, the Masyumi members and sympathizers for two days were taught about political and social sciences, both from the perspective of Western science and from the perspective of Islamic theology. Some of the subjects taught were the issue of foreign policy, economic upheaval, the struggle of the workers, the structure of the state 27 “Haloean kita: ‘koordinasi dan konsolidasi. 28 Ibid. 29 Ibid. Muhammad Yuanda Zara JOURNAL OF INDONESIAN ISLAM Volume 13, Number 01, June 2019 128 according to Islam, and the procedures for the struggle of the Sabil army (the army of the holy war). 30 Becoming Muslims and Patriots The GPII’s Articles of Association and By-Laws (Anggaran Rumah Tangga) showed a combination of Islam and nationalism. As published by Boelan Sabit, in the Article 4 of GPII’s Articles of Association, it was mentioned that the aim of the GPII was twofold, namely: “Upholding Islam” and “Defending and perfecting the State of the Republic of Indonesia based on the Belief in One God”. This was clearly GPII acceptance of Pancasila instead of the Jakarta Charter, the early version of the Pancasila text which was in one of its articles emphasized the application of Islamic law to Indonesian Muslims. The requirement to become GPII member was provided in the first article of its By-laws: “Islamic youth, citizens of the Republic of Indonesia”, aged between 15-35 years. 31 The bond between Islam and nationalism was manifested in a symbolic form. The GPII meeting on 26-27 December 1945 gave an idea on how to become Muslim as well as a patriot of Indonesia in the time of war. At this meeting the audience stood up to sing Indonesian national anthem, ‘Indonesia Raya’, led by Abd. Madjid Harsoloemakso. The meeting itself was closed by shouting Allahu akbar (Allah is great) three times and merdeka (independence) once.32 However, this emphasis on the combination of Islam and Indonesian patriotism was not only represented in the conceptual and symbolic form. For Boelan Sabit, a pious Muslim at the same time could also be a patriot. Boelan Sabit often published the true story of Muslim youth who were willing to sacrifice their lives to defend Indonesia’s independence. One rather long story that represented a great sacrificial narrative by Muslim youth for an independent Indonesian state could be seen in the story of a member of the GPII Surakarta and Hizboelloh (Masyumi’s armed youth organization) named Banani. The story of the struggle of Banani took almost half a page in the newspaper, showing its major value and importance. In the midst of the many news about political developments at the national level, this 30 “Boeah koersoes kilat,” Boelan Sabit, 10 January 1946. 31 “Anggaran Dasar Gerakan Pemoeda. 32 “Rapat oemoem moe’tamar GPII. Defending the State, Defending the Religion 129 JOURNAL OF INDONESIAN ISLAM Volume 13, Number 01, June 2019 personal story showed that a touching story about a young man’s sacrifice was extremely noteworthy. The title of the news is ‘Kenang- kenangan bagi: Pahlawan A. BANANI-SIRADJ Hizboelloh’ (A Piece of Memory for a hero named A. BANANI-SIRADJ Hizboelloh). 33 The article narrated the last eight days in Banani’s life. On the morning of Tuesday, 18 December 1945, Barisan Hizboelloh Surakarta was holding a rally to prepare troops for battle. Banani was present. This group was visited by President Soekarno, his family, and his ministers. In his remarks, Soekarno emphasized the importance of Hizboelloh in sustaining an independent Indonesian state from enemy interference as well as in helping this new country to prosper in the future. 34 Sukarno’s advice described by Boelan Sabit “strengthening his [Banani] soul and determination, that Hizboelloh was willing to sacrifice for the state, for the sake of prosperous Indonesia”.35 In the afternoon, the Hizboelloh troops moved to the battlefield. They, wrote Boelan Sabit journalist, “had reinforced their minds that they would not return, intending to water the earth of the Indonesian motherland with their blood”.36 On 24 December 1945, Hizboelloh troops were ordered to retreat after carrying out an attack (not specified where and how the raid went). But Banani (and his two friends) refused to withdraw, and asked to be sent back to the front line. Banani was ordered to take a rest by his commander, but for him, there was no such thing as taking rest for Muslim youth, because the real rest, he said, was “later if we have arrived at the God’s protection”. Banani also bathed many times in order to remain pure from hadath (ritual impurity). He incessantly voiced his desire to meet God. He read Quran after the battle. He told his friends that he missed martyrdom. He recounted his dream, where he received purely white and fragrant flowers from heaven. He also saw a golden gate with a beautiful guard. He tried to approach the gate, but he could not reach it because his dream suddenly stopped. When 33 “Kenang-kenangan bagi: Pahlawan A. BANANI-SIRADJ Hizboelloh,” Boelan Sabit, 21 December 1945. 34 Ibid. 35 Ibid. 36 Ibid. Muhammad Yuanda Zara JOURNAL OF INDONESIAN ISLAM Volume 13, Number 01, June 2019 130 he woke up, his hands smelled good. His friends admitted that Banani’s hands smelled like musk. 37 Shortly thereafter, came the order from their commanders to get ready to fight. Two days later, on December 26, they met NICA (Netherlands Indies Civil Administration) and Gurkha forces in Ungaran, northern Central Java. As they crawled near the enemy, they were bombarded with bullets and mortars. Hizboelloh troops pushed forward while shouting Alla>hu akbar and La> ila>ha illalla>h (There is no god but Allah). There were a few casualties on the Hizboelloh side. One of them was Banani. His body was taken to Surakarta Hospital, and then brought to a Republic office in Surakarta. In this last place Banani’s body was given an “Islamic army” honor. Boelan Sabit reported that the office space was crowded by the military and GPII members, as well as Muslims of the city in general. The officials read aloud the biography of Banani and messages for those who were still alive. After that, military honors were given by firing rifles three times. Banani’s body was then buried in the Astana Bahagia cemetary. The journey of Banani’s body to the tomb, Boelan Sabit wrote, was escorted by “tens of thousands of people”.38 The death of Banani (and one other friend) on the Ungaran front was depicted by Boelan Sabit as the death of martyrs. The death was portrayed giving an extra enthusiasm to other Hizboelloh fighters to control the Ungaran region. It was reported that in the end Hizboelloh troops succeeded in repelling NICA and Gurkha forces. A number of NICA and Gurkha soldiers were killed, while their weapons were confiscated by Hizboelloh troops. Dozens of enemy spies were also arrested. In short, Hizboelloh, Boelan Sabit journalist wrote, acted as “banteng ketaton” (wounded bull who raged till dead) to resist the attacks of NICA and Gurkha, which ended in victory on the part of Hizboelloh, marked by the takeover of Djatingaleh Fortress in Semarang by Hizboelloh troops. 39 The similar stories as above appeared many times in Boelan Sabit, with this Banani story as one of the most elaborated ones.40 The core 37 Ibid. 38 Ibid. 39 Ibid. 40 Another example is the story of Moeh. Solihan, a Hizboelloh member who was killed by enemy attacks. See ‘Kenang-kenangan bagi: Pahlawan Moeh. Solihan Hizboelloh’, Boelan Sabit, 2 January 1946. Defending the State, Defending the Religion 131 JOURNAL OF INDONESIAN ISLAM Volume 13, Number 01, June 2019 theme of these stories was similar, namely about the sacrifice of a pious Muslim youth who at the same time really patriotic in defending Indonesia from the Dutch and the British. During their lives, they were devout adherents of Islam and did many good deeds to others. They were not only pious personally, but also dared to defend their religion and country. In the end, they died on the battlefield and were described as martyrs for both their religion and country. In turn, this kind of story did not only stop in the narrative, but was expected to be an inspiration and a mental reinforcement for other Muslim youths going into the battle. For Boelan Sabit, they were portrayed as patriotic martyrs, who later died on the battlefield as Indonesian independence heroes. The burial of their dead bodies was arranged militarily as well as according to Islamic rituals. All GPII members and local Muslims were depicted in mourning for their death and were ready to continue their aspirations for an independent Indonesia. In addition to the biography of the martyrs, Boelan Sabit praised the deceased Indonesian Muslim fighters through poetry. One of them was entitled “Kenang2an kepada Pahlawan jg telah sjahid” (Remembrance to a hero who died as martyr) written by a poet named Bima Sutji, published in Boelan Sabit on 2 January 1946. The poem read as follows: Mr. X is lying on bed, finely wrapped in shroud, fully decorated, to be taken to the tomb, He... is Dead. People say. And you... o hero, a leading warrior, your body rolled on the ground. your body was covered by blood. You died, people say. Mr. X is DEAD, and you too, DEAD, in the end there is no difference, because all is the will of ALLAH. Muhammad Yuanda Zara JOURNAL OF INDONESIAN ISLAM Volume 13, Number 01, June 2019 132 The only difference is that you are DEAD because of your devotion, defending the Homeland and Religion, You are DEAD in the path of Allah.41 Another poem, “Djika” (If), in Boelan Sabit, 7 January 1946, written by Alimoeddin, read as follows: Hero... If. Black smoke is steaming, The sound of weapons disrupts nature The loud sound seemed to split the earth Inside the jungle, city and village, On steep hills and cliffs, Or perhaps in a deep valley... Around the water, the fire to... the edge of the death: Strengthen your heart, calming down your soul, Being sincere Release your feelings in memories, You died as a hero, Upholding Religion, defending the Land. Let the body be covered in blood, Shouting out before life [text unclear] Allah is Great, Allah is Great, Allh is Great, Independent, always Independent. No God but Allah…42 The tone of the poems above seemed dark because they contained the terms such as blood, shroud, dead and tomb. However, optimism was present. Death was God’s will and none could escape death. Yet, the death of freedom fighters was of higher value, because they died while defending their religion and homeland. In the view of Boelan Sabit, this was the most ideal type of hero in a time of conflict between Indonesia and the foreign enemies. The poets, as well as the Boelan Sabit which published it, praised the sacrifices of these martyrs and positioned them as role models for other Muslim youth. 41 “Kenang2an kepada Pahlawan jg telah sjahid,” Boelan Sabit, 2 January 1946. 42 “Djika,” Boelan Sabit, 7 January 1946. Defending the State, Defending the Religion 133 JOURNAL OF INDONESIAN ISLAM Volume 13, Number 01, June 2019 Besides the call for Indonesian Muslims to contribute with their lives, they were also requested to provide financial assistance to support the independence struggle, especially in the form of money. Masyumi Party formed the so-called Fonds Sabilillah as an effort to attract financial support from Muslims. The campaigns to request financial aid from Muslims were carried out, one of which was through advertisement in Boelan Sabit. Masyumi Party in its advert in Boelan Sabit, 10 January 1946, hoped for “maximum assistance” from Muslims throughout Indonesia especially to strengthen Sabilillah and Hizboelloh. The money was expected to be delivered to the Masyumi head office in Setjodiningratan 1, Yogyakarta. 43 ‘Ulama>’ and the Independence for Struggle In the pre-war era, ‘ulama>’ (Muslim scholars) were identical with religious teachers who taught their students with religious education in centers of religious education such as surau (small mosque) or pesantren (Islamic boarding school). They almost entirely focused on educating people to understand religious teachings. Only a few of them were involved in political affairs. Dutch policies limited the movement of religious teachers, including via 1905 and 1925 Teacher Ordinance, Hajj passport policy, and screening of returning pilgrims from Mecca. These had narrowed the space for religious teachers to be involved in matters beyond their mosques. However, the arrival of the Japanese enabled Muslim scholars to take part in managing the community, even though in the context of supporting Japan’s war effort in the Pacific. This can be seen, among other things, in the involvement of Indonesian scholars in Japan- established organizations. After the Japanese defeat and the proclamation of Indonesian independence, the influential scholars’ society repositioned themselves, this time as supporters of the independent Indonesian state. Boelan Sabit proposed the need to unite two important elements in Indonesian society, namely Muslim scholars and Western-educated intellectuals. A writer named Matapatjar wrote in Boelan Sabit that every group in Indonesian society must contribute to the Republic of Indonesia in accordance with their respective backgrounds. The writers, he explained, contributed by writing in newspapers and 43 “Fonds Sabilillah,” Boelan Sabit, 10 January 1946. Muhammad Yuanda Zara JOURNAL OF INDONESIAN ISLAM Volume 13, Number 01, June 2019 134 magazines, while the agitators contributed with their voices to make people aware. The organizers, he continued, struggled to arrange the steps of struggle, whereas the wealthy people struggled by donating their wealth and the knights struggled with their blood and soul. The other two important parties were Muslim scholars and intellectuals. The ‘ulama>’ had the role of “being the leader” while the intellectuals “became promoters, holding the steering wheel responsible for the nation and their homeland”. These two groups, said Matapatjar, must unite “to organize the people’s energy in facing this fierce struggle”.44 He continued: With the unity between ‘Ulama >’ and intellectuals, one can guarantee the firm unity of the people. Therefore, intellectuals, who are full of modern knowledge, and ‘Ulama >’, who are always learning the contents of the Quran that are full of knowledge and sciences, such as natural sciences, medical science, astronomy, social sciences, political science, social sciences, etc. must unite to bring and guide the people to a direction of progress and to uphold the eternal the State of the Republic of Indonesia. 45 In the GPII conference in late December 1945, Chairperson of the Yogyakarta Regional KNIP, Moh. Saleh, also gave a speech, which was then published in Boelan Sabit. He said that after observing various battlefronts he found that the role of the kyai (traditional Muslim clerics) at the time of independence, differed from their role in the past. Previously, he said, the clerics’ major task was to memorize the so-called “fa ‘ala jaf‘oeloe” (Arabic verbs). However, now in the age of independence the situation had changed. The clerics left their surau and pesantren to be involved in handling socio-political matters. He believed that the clerics had at least two important contributions. 46 First, they were deemed skillful at managing the newly born state in their capacity as residents and regents. Second, they became “heroes who cleanse rioters and enemies”. For Moh. Saleh, the kyai and santri (Muslim students) were nothing but “flowers on the battlefield today”. The kyai 44 “Oelama dan intellek bersatoelah oentoek menegakkan negara Repoeblik Indonesia,”, Boelan Sabit, 26 December 1945. 45 Ibid. 46 ‘Rapat oemoem moe’tamar GPII. Defending the State, Defending the Religion 135 JOURNAL OF INDONESIAN ISLAM Volume 13, Number 01, June 2019 in the independence war, Moh. Saleh added, had dual functions, namely “war heroes” and “excellent state experts”.47 The kyai themselves did not only play a role in calling for resistance against the British and the Dutch. Even though they were already old in term of age, they were still willing to join training for preparation to enter the battlefield. One of such training was held by Sabilillah on 1 January 1946 at his headquarters. A report in Boelan Sabit mentioned that at that time there were at least 300 kyai who were trained in weapons handling and military tactics. They were mostly old people, which was marked by their beards (they were then dubbed “Barisan Djenggot” [The Beards Front]).48 Why did these old people join the training for battle? One of the kyai asserted that he joined the training in order to “understand how to beat Gurkha and NICA”. After this training, he intended going to Semarang to hamper NICA and Gurkha movement. He was ready to live and to die; he said, if he died he would be a martyr, and if he was still alive then he would live in freedom. He had prepared his own weapon to face the NICA and Gurkha troops: sharpened bamboo spears. 49 Since January 1946, Sabilillah Surakarta had even organized special military training for elders, dubbed as “peradjoerit barisan oeban” (gray warrior soldiers). They were generally aged 50 years and above. In his report entitled “Barisan Sabilillah” (Sabilillah Front), Boelan Sabit reported that they were trained by a Republican military major who understood military science. In the afternoon they were trained to use hand grenades, incendiary device, and spears and how to carry out attacks on the enemy. They were portrayed as elders who had young spirit because they wanted to practice their military drill which required strong body like that of young people. In addition, Boelan Sabit illustrated them as devout elders, because at night after military training they “face God with prayer and reflection”.50 47 Ibid. 48 “Latihan Barisan Sabilillah,” Boelan Sabit, 2 January 1946. 49 Ibid. 50 “Barisan Sabilillah,” Boelan Sabit, 10 January 1946. Muhammad Yuanda Zara JOURNAL OF INDONESIAN ISLAM Volume 13, Number 01, June 2019 136 Conclusion After researching the Boelan Sabit newspaper’s various articles for a month (from 15 December 1945 to 14 January 1946), it was found that this newspaper incessantly called for Indonesian Muslims to defend Indonesian independence from Dutch colonialism and British occupation. This call, according to the newspaper, was based on both Islam and nationalism. Boelan Sabit ensured its Muslim readers that the period of independence was a time to strengthen the two identities inherent in them, namely a son of Indonesia and a Muslim. This newspaper, by taking the legitimacy and inspiration to maintain Indonesian independence from the Quran and other Islamic teachings, constantly voiced that Indonesian Muslims upheld the Republic of Indonesia whose existence was challenged by the Dutch and the British. Besides, it believed that adhering Islam correctly would be an important thing to do to bring the postwar world to peace and progress. To support Indonesian independence from foreign attackers, some methods used by Bulan Sabit to express this standpoint were, first, it linked various stories taken from Islamic traditions to the struggle of Indonesian Muslims to maintain their country’s independence. For example, on 15 December 1945, when Muslims all over the world commemorated 10th Muharram (Ashura Day). For Boelan Sabit, Indonesian Muslims who at that time were struggling to maintain their independence must learn from the messages brought by the commemoration of Ashura Day, including by studying the great sacrifices of the prophets to reach happiness. Second, it emphasized that the Indonesian people were not alone in their fighting to defend their independence. They had many fellows throughout Asia and Africa. Third, it criticized the failure of the Western countries to fulfil their pre-war promises, which stressed that colonized nations were allowed to determine their future. As a media for public literacy, this newspaper not only voiced the views of its mother organization (Masyumi), but also sought to educate its Muslim readers, especially concerning on matters of state. There were not many Indonesians could read and write Latin letters, and even fewer were politically literate. Thus, GPII, as the publisher of Boelan Sabit, made this magazine a medium for sharing information about the modern political concepts and information about political developments within and outside the country. Defending the State, Defending the Religion 137 JOURNAL OF INDONESIAN ISLAM Volume 13, Number 01, June 2019 Judging from its reports and views, Boelan Sabit continuously campaigned that a pious Muslim can at the same time be a patriotic Indonesian son. In its Article of Association, the GPII clearly stated that they aimed both to uphold Islam and to defend the Republic of Indonesia. They accepted Pancasila and believed in a representative democracy. And, to prove that the combination of pious Muslims and patriotic sons of Indonesia was real, Boelan Sabit repeatedly reported on the sacrifices of Islamic youth in the fight against the Dutch and the British troops. Reports of Indonesian nationalist newspapers on the events of the death of Indonesian fighters generally focused on the sacrifice of the young men in the context of the defence of the motherland. However, Boelan Sabit combined the defense of the motherland with the sacrifice of a martyr to defend his religion. Therefore, for Masyumi and Boelan Sabit, an ideal type of Muslim at that time was a man devout to his religion, being kind to others, loving the country and willing to sacrifice his life for his religion and nation. In addition to the youth, Boelan Sabit believed that the presence and contribution of ‘ulama>’ (Muslim scholars) were indispensable in the struggle for maintaining Indonesian independence. In the past the scholars may only concentrated on religious matters, but now they had taken part in social and political matters as well. They were reported joining in military drill and weapons handling. More importantly, given their educational background, they were illustrated to have sufficient knowledge and skills not only about the management of the people but especially the management of the state. ‘Ulama>’, thus, were redefined by Boelan Sabit, by equating them with intellectuals and administrators. This research shows that Indonesian nationalism in its formative years must be understood in the context of its relation to Islamic ideas. This is evident in Islamic oriented print media such as Boelan Sabit. Reading Boelan Sabit enable us to comprehend how the idea of nationalism was combined with the idea of Islam in the context of the Indonesian war of independence and was then expressed in Islamic oriented newspapers. [] Muhammad Yuanda Zara JOURNAL OF INDONESIAN ISLAM Volume 13, Number 01, June 2019 138 References Books and Articles Benda, Harry J. The Crescent and Rising Sun: Indonesian Islam under Japanese Occupation, 1942-1945. The Hague and Bandung: W. Van Hoeve, 1958. Anderson, Benedict. Revoloesi Pemoeda: Pendudukan Jepang dan Perlawanan di Jawa, 1944-1946. Jakarta: Sinar Harapan, 1988. Chaniago, J.R. et. al. Ditugaskan Sejarah: Perjuangan Merdeka, 1945-1985. Jakarta: Pustaka Merdeka, 1987. Hill, David T. Journalism and Politics in Indonesia: A Critical Biography of Mochtar Lubis (1922-2004) as Editor and Author. Oxon & New York: Routledge, 2010. Luttikhuis, Bart & A. Dirk Moses (eds.). Colonial Counterinsurgency and Mass Violence: The Dutch Empire in Indonesia. Oxon & New York: Routledge, 2014. Madinier, Rémy. Islam and Politics in Indonesia: The Masyumi Party between Democracy and Integralism. Singapore: NUS Press, 2015. Poeze, Harry A. Tan Malaka, Gerakan Kiri, dan Revolusi Indonesia. Jilid 2: Maret 1946-Maret 1947. Jakarta: Yayasan Obor Indonesia & KITLV, 2009. Sachsman, David B., S. Kittrell Rushing, and Roy Morris Jr. (eds). Words at war: The Civil War and American Journalism. Indiana: Purdue University Press, 2008. Suwirta, Andi. Suara dari Dua Kota: Revolusi Indonesia dalam Pandangan Surat Kabar “Merdeka” (Jakarta) dan “Kedaulatan Rakjat” (Yogyakarta) 1945-1947. Jakarta: Balai Pustaka, 2000. Toer, Pramoedya Ananta et. al. Kronik Revolusi Indonesia Bagian I (1945). Jakarta: KPG, 1999. Wilkinson, Glenn R. Depictions and images of war in Edwardian newspapers, 1899-1914. Hampshire and New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2003. Defending the State, Defending the Religion 139 JOURNAL OF INDONESIAN ISLAM Volume 13, Number 01, June 2019 Newspapers “Anggaran Dasar Gerakan Pemoeda Islam Indonesia”. Boelan Sabit, 29 December 1945. “Anggaran Roemah Tangga Gerakan Pemoeda Islam Indonesia”. Boelan Sabit, 29 December 1945. “Barisan Sabilillah”. Boelan Sabit, 10 January 1946. “Boeah koersoes kilat”. Boelan Sabit, 10 January 1946. Boelan Sabit, 15 December 1945. “Boelan Sabit djadi pertjatoeran”. Boelan Sabit, 14 January 1946. “Demokrasi”. Boelan Sabit, 15 December 1945. “Djika”. Boelan Sabit, 7 January 1946. “Fonds Sabilillah”. Boelan Sabit, 10 January 1946. “Haloean kita: ‘Kedaulatan Rakjat’”. Boelan Sabit, 14 January 1946. “Haloean kita: ‘koordinasi dan konsolidasi’”. Boelan Sabit, 7 January 1946. “Kenang-kenangan bagi: Pahlawan A. BANANI-SIRADJ Hizboelloh”. Boelan Sabit, 21 December 1945. “Kenang-kenangan bagi: Pahlawan Moeh. Solihan Hizboelloh”. Boelan Sabit, 2 January 1946. “Kenang2an kepada Pahlawan jg telah sjahid”. Boelan Sabit, 2 January 1946. “Latihan Barisan Sabilillah”. Boelan Sabit, 2 January 1946. “Menebalkan semangat tjinta bangsa”. Boelan Sabit, 15 December 1945. “Menoedjoe djalan kebahagiaan”. Boelan Sabit, 14 January 1946. “Moe’tamar GPII di kota Bengawan”. Boelan Sabit, 26 December 1945. “Oelama dan intellek bersatoelah oentoek menegakkan negara Repoeblik Indonesia”. Boelan Sabit, 26 December 1945. “Perdjoeangan rakjat sebagai banteng ketaton”. Boelan Sabit, 26 December 1945. Muhammad Yuanda Zara JOURNAL OF INDONESIAN ISLAM Volume 13, Number 01, June 2019 140 “Rapat oemoem moe’tamar GPII”. Boelan Sabit, 29 December 1945. “Revolusi dan Islam”. Boelan Sabit, 26 December 1945. “Roeangan Pengetahoean dan Politik: ‘Dominion Status’ Arti dan Isinja”. Boelan Sabit, 2 January 1946. “Roeangan Pengetahoean dan Politik: ‘Dominion Status’, Arti dan Isinja”. article 2, Boelan Sabit, 7 January 1946. “Sepoeloeh Moeharom (‘Asjoero)”. Boelan Sabit, 15 December 1945. “Soerat Insjiqoq”. Boelan Sabit, 26 December 1945. “Tindjauan: Doenia terbakar lagi?”. Boelan Sabit, 15 December 1945. work_4pxvv4gadrak7hu4rgap3fkm64 ---- Are transcendental theories of justice redundant 1 Are transcendental theories of justice redundant? Forthcoming in a booksymposium in The Journal of Economic Methodology, with a reply by Amartya Sen. Ingrid Robeyns  (robeyns < at> fwb.eur.nl) Final pre-publication version 8 November 2010 Amartya Sen’s The Idea of Justice is a very rich book, with many aspects worth discussing. I will limit myself here to one major claim that Sen makes, namely that transcendental theories of justice are redundant. I will argue that this ‘Redundancy Claim’ is mistaken, since for justice- enhancing actions we need both transcendental and non-transcendental theorising of justice. Nevertheless I endorse an implication of the Redundancy Claim, namely that theorists of justice should shift their focus from transcendental theorizing towards thinking about justice- enhancing change, thereby restoring the balance between transcendental and non-transcendental theorizing. I will argue that this ‘Rebalancing Claim’ not only follows from the (mistaken) Redundancy Claim, but also from another argument which Sen advances about the current practice of philosophers of justice. I will conclude that the Redundancy Claim has to be rejected, but that this is not a big loss, since what is really important is the Rebalancing Claim, which is vindicated. Transcendental theories and the Redundancy Claim How does Sen understand transcendental theories of justice? Transcendental theories of justice are theories that describe a perfectly just situation: no further justice-improvements are possible. Transcendental theory “concentrates its attention on what it identifies as perfect justice, rather than on relative comparisons of justice and injustice. It tries only to identify social characteristics that cannot be transcended in terms of justice, and its focus is thus not on comparing feasible societies, all of which may fall short of the ideals of perfection. The inquiry is aimed at identifying the nature of ‘the just’, rather than finding some criteria for an alternative being ‘less unjust’ than another.” (p. 5-6). Sen argues that transcendental theories are redundant if our aim is to actually make choices that advance justice: “If a theory of justice is to guide reasoned choice of policies, strategies or institutions, then the identification of fully just social arrangements is neither necessary nor sufficient” (p. 15). Call this the Redundancy Claim. I agree with one part of the Redundancy Claim, namely that transcendental theory is not sufficient for guidance, and will therefore only 2 focus on the claim that it is not necessary. This latter part of the Redundancy Claim I believe to be mistaken. Sen argues that a number of basic injustices don’t need transcendental theory in order for us to understand and agree that they concern gross injustices (xi-xii). Indeed, all theories of justice would agree that corruption in politics, power abuse by economic actors, or the training of child soldiers are blatant cases of injustice, and that we don’t need a transcendental theory of justice to spell that out. Yet we cannot extrapolate from this particular subset of injustices (i.e. manifest and clearly remediable cases of injustice) to the entire set of injustices. My belief is that the usefulness of transcendental theory is limited and currently enjoys a too high status among academic philosophers, but that we are mistaken if we believe that we can entirely do without. Two arguments against the Redundancy Claim I will offer two arguments against the Redundancy Claim. The first argument is that many cases of injustice are complex and often subtle, and therefore more difficult to identify and analyse as cases of injustice than cases of basic injustice. Take the case of gender justice in liberal societies, which have seen many decades of feminist activism, and where most citizens explicitly support equal rights for men and women. In those societies, many citizens believe that gender justice is fully realised. But how do we judge a claim of full or perfect justice? If we want to analyse a claim of perfect gender justice, we need transcendental principles of justice. We need to specify which conditions have to be met before we consider a certain state of affairs as perfectly just. In order to assess such a claim of gender justice, one needs principles that tell us when a society is gender just. These principles are transcendental principles of justice (even though they are only transcendental in one domain, namely gender relations). Often the most effective way to argue for a claim of an injustice that is not blatant, is by arguing for ideals of justice, that is, arguing for principles of transcendental justice (in general, or in a particular domain), and empirically showing that these principles are not met. Again, social activists make ample use of such transcendental principles of justice and of this kind of public reasoning, for example when they invoke an ideal of substantive equality of opportunity. Summing up, judgments about the comparison of complex cases of injustice implicitly or explicitly do refer to ideals of justice. Not just in academic work, but also in real-life public discussions. The second argument for the non-redundancy of transcendental theories stems from the nature of the non-transcendental theorising of justice, which is the theorising that guides our justice-enhancing actions and policies. Non-transcendental theorising of justice entails but is not limited to the comparative approach to justice, the approach that Sen champions in The Idea of Justice. For example, non-transcendental theorising of justice also includes theorising on 3 how to weigh different principles of justice, or theorising on what to do if in the long run we can achieve a more just state, but whereby this requires sacrificing one generation for the sake of the following generations. I believe that non-transcendental theories of justice require transcendental theories. Non- transcendental theories of justice give us a chain of changes that are needed in order to reach the most just social state among all feasible social states. We need to have a complete ‘navigation map’, a clear vision of how to go from where we are to where we want to be. We need an entire path of justice-enhancing actions, not only a comparison between two states which comparative justice offers us. If we limit ourselves to the comparative approach, we may choose for an injustice-reducing action that may benefit us in the short run, but may lead us to a suboptimal situation (from the point of view of justice) in the long run, due to the path- dependency of our actions. Suppose that we can represent the degree of justice of a certain situation with a number, on a scale where 100 represents the fully just social state. The initial social state A has a justice- value of 50. From A we can move to either B or S, with B corresponding to a justice value of 70 and S of 55. If we are in A, and only compare B and S, then the conclusion is easy: we have to take action so that we end up in social state B. But our possibilities for further action are not independent of this first choice. Suppose that in the best-case scenario we can move from B to C, with C having a justice value of 80. From S, however, we will be able to move to T where we can realize a justice value of 95. We cannot move from B to T. It then becomes clear that in order to make a reasoned decision between B and S, we need to know the ‘paths of change’ that B and S are on, and those paths are directing us towards an ideal, that is, a transcendental theory. Clearly the comparative approach is an important element of this more complete story of how to decide what to do – but that complete story also needs a vision of the ultimate goal, that is, a transcendental theory of justice. Thus, I conclude that transcendental theory is in non- basic cases necessary for justice-enhancing change, and that therefore the Redundancy Claim is mistaken. Note that my arguments against the general validity of the Redundancy Claim do not require that there is an agreement on the transcendental principles of justice, or that these principles are completely spelled out in each and every detail. If there is no agreement, then each disagreeing party will need its own transcendental principles in order to make up their own minds about which injustice-reducing actions to defend. Similarly, completeness is not required for transcendental theories to be useful; in fact, many transcendental principles of justice are plural and often somewhat vague and thus require further interpretation before they can be put into practice. But even if a transcendental account of justice is incomplete, or even if it consists of a plurality of principles which need to be weighted by public reasoning or by intuition, it 4 does give us a set of standards or ideals against which to judge different possible paths of social change. The ‘navigation maps’ which we require to guide reasoned choice of policies, strategies and institutions for questions of non-blatant injustices must include a specification of our ultimate goal, that is, transcendental principles of justice. Vindicating the Rebalancing Claim So far I have advanced two arguments for why I believe that the Redundancy Claim is not correct. Yet suppose the redundancy claim were correct: what would have been its implications? A weak implication would be that theorists of justice devote too much attention and energy to transcendental theory, since it is neither necessary nor sufficient for our ultimate goal, which is to reduce injustices. Still, transcendental theory would play some other useful role, and we therefore shouldn’t abolish it entirely. Rather, we should restore the balance between the attention we devote to transcendental theory and non-transcendental theory. A stronger implication would be that theorists of justice should stop conducting all transcendental theorising, since it does not contribute anything towards that goal or any other valuable goal. I don’t think Sen would endorse the strong implication, given how important he judges John Rawls’s theory of justice to be, which Sen believes to be a transcendental theory. I read Sen’s work, both in The Idea of Justice and other work, as supporting the weak implication. Sen’s concern is that theories of justice should ultimately be ‘practical’. Sen describes the aim of the theory of justice as “to clarify how we can proceed to address questions of enhancing justice and removing injustice, rather than to offer resolutions of questions about the nature of perfect injustice” (p. ix). Not all philosophers espouse this view: some believe that the proper role of political philosophy is not to answer the question what to do, but rather to seek the truth, whether or not the truth makes any difference to what we should do. Of course, the truth-seeking and the practical need not be mutually exclusive. Indeed, the practical approach to justice needs to be based on true knowledge about the world and about justice, since otherwise the guidance that the philosopher harvests from her reasoning may be misleading. Yet we don’t necessarily need to know the full truth, and all possible details of the truth: at some point the added value to practice of further truth-seeking knowledge becomes infinitesimally small, and may therefore not be the best use of our scarce time. There is a growing feeling among some political philosophers that we have reached that point, and that the status incentives in (Anglo-American) academic philosophy departments are biased in favour of those seeking further details regarding the truth of justice, even if the added practical value has become tiny, and despite the fact that enormous amounts of work need to be done in non-transcendental theory. If we really care about justice, and not merely enjoy the intellectual stimulation that political philosophy offers, we should be doing something about it, 5 for example by collaborating with policy scholars in figuring out how to design philosophically-sound justice-enhancing policies, or collaborating with critical citizens or social activists in thinking about how to effectively analyse cases of gross injustice, including those that are caused by the state. Yet that kind of ‘applied’ or ‘interdisciplinary’ work, which is often muddy and not elegant at all, doesn’t enjoy high status in Anglo-American political philosophy. Are we having our priorities right? Sen argues in The Idea of Justice that mainstream theorists of justice have their priorities wrong: “Importance must be attached to the starting point, in particular the selection of some question to be answered (for example, ‘how would justice be advanced?’), rather than others (for example, ‘what would be perfectly just institutions?’). … Given the present balance of emphases in contemporary political philosophy, this will require a radical change in the formulation of the theory of justice” (9). Let me call the argument that we need to shift the nature of contemporary theorizing about justice away from the transcendental truth-seeking, towards the practical, and thereby also rearrange and rebalance the status that we allocate to different types of philosophical enquiry, the Rebalancing Claim. The Rebalancing Claim is a weak implication of the Redundancy Claim, and this may perhaps explain Sen’s insistence on the Redundancy Claim. Yet the Rebalancing Claim also follows from Sen’s general argument about the present dominant practice of contemporary theories of justice. In fact, I believe that many philosophers working on specific cases of injustice, such as global justice, gender justice, or environmental justice, reject the Redundancy Claim but endorse the Rebalancing Claim. That particular position acknowledges that transcendental theory does have a role to play, but that it currently enjoys too much status and receives too much attention in academia, and that therefore its role should be much more limited than is currently the case. If the Redundancy Claim is mistaken but the Rebalancing Claim can be convincingly argued for, then I believe that nothing important is lost, and that the claim that is really important is vindicated. Yet while I agree with the Rebalancing Claim, I do have one qualification to add. In one respect I think Sen is too pessimistic in his characterisation of contemporary theorising about justice, since much of the kind of work that he is advocating is already being conducted. For example, there is a huge literature on particular aspects of global injustices, ranging from Iris Marion Young’s analysis of individual and collective responsibilities for the employment conditions of workers in sweatshops, to Leif Weinar’s analysis of why the sale of oil by dictators in oil-rich African countries to oil companies in Europe and the US is a severe property rights violation of the afflicted African populations. 1 These are examples of excellent pieces of theorizing about concrete cases of injustice. If one looks carefully, and not only in the most prestigious journals, there is a huge literature out there that does analyse such cases of 6 injustices, though it may not always attract the spotlights to the same degree as the universal theories of Rawls, Nozick, Dworkin, and others. In my reading of the contemporary literature on justice and injustices, the problem is not so much that this kind of research is not taking place, but rather that among too many philosophers it doesn’t enjoy high status and is not considered ‘theorising about justice’ but rather classified as applied ethics or case studies on injustices. Such attitude underestimates the importance of this type of analysis. Thus, my assessment of the situation differs from Sen’s assessment in so far as I think that the kind of work he is advocating does happen; I rather think the problem lies in the limited status and the non-canonical position of this work compared to more abstract, universal, general theorising about justice. I am grateful to Martijn Boot, Pablo Gilabert, Anca Gheaus, Anders Schinkel and commentators at Crooked Timber for very helpful comments and illuminating discussions, and to the Netherlands Organisation for Scientific Research (NWO) for research funding. 1 Iris Marion Young (2004) ‘Responsibility and global labour justice’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 12(4), pp. 365-388; Leif Weinar (2008) ‘Property Rights and the Resource Curse’, Philosophy and Public affairs, 36(1), pp. 2-32. work_4qkxdq4ijngstkger2hww6mytm ---- None work_4r4qd7mmczap3jcxajkk442voq ----                City, University of London Institutional Repository Citation: Birkett, G. (2018). Influencing the Penal Agenda? The Justice Select Committee and ‘Transforming Justice’, 2010–15. The Political Quarterly, doi: 10.1111/1467-923X.12480 This is the accepted version of the paper. This version of the publication may differ from the final published version. Permanent repository link: http://openaccess.city.ac.uk/18900/ Link to published version: http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/1467-923X.12480 Copyright and reuse: City Research Online aims to make research outputs of City, University of London available to a wider audience. Copyright and Moral Rights remain with the author(s) and/or copyright holders. URLs from City Research Online may be freely distributed and linked to. City Research Online: http://openaccess.city.ac.uk/ publications@city.ac.uk City Research Online http://openaccess.city.ac.uk/ mailto:publications@city.ac.uk 1 Influencing the Penal Agenda? The Justice Select Committee and ‘Transforming Justice’, 2010-15 Gemma Birkett Keywords: Justice Select Committee, Parliamentary oversight, political influence, Coalition government, Transforming Rehabilitation. Abstract This article assesses the policy influence of the House of Commons Justice Select Committee, established to oversee the work of the Ministry of Justice following its creation a decade ago. The Committee has, from the outset, overseen many contentious policy and legislative developments in the penal field, although none so extensive as those introduced following the formation of the Conservative-Liberal Democrat Coalition government in 2010. Despite the newsworthy nature of its business, the Committee has, to some extent, operated in the shadows of its high-profile sister, the Home Affairs Select Committee, and has received surprisingly limited attention from criminologists and political scientists alike. Forming part of a wider investigation into the work of the Committee, this article examines the extent to which it was able to influence penal developments during the Coalition years. This period is of particular interest given that it heralded the end of the New Labour administration and welcomed the ‘fresh thinking’ of a Coalition leadership keen to emphasise its progressive attitude towards law and order. While the Committee was able to influence the direction of penal policy on several occasions this mostly occurred as a result of its proactive or niche inquiries. The Committee had less impact when conducting inquiries that assessed the government’s flagship policy agenda, however. Such findings brought into question the ability of the Committee to influence the most significant justice transformations in this era of new penal governance. Introduction This article involves the first empirical analysis of the work of the House of Commons Justice Select Committee from 2010-15. Outlined in the introduction to this Special Issue, the period 2010-15 heralded fundamental changes to the penal landscape. The Coalition government’s ambitious reforms permeated all areas of criminal justice, including fundamental developments in probation, the courts and administrative justice. The Ministry of Justice was one of the greatest casualties of Chancellor George Osborne’s financial axe, swallowing an overall budget cut of over a third between 2010-2015. Reforms in the penal sphere reflected the commitment 2 to austerity and were couched in the language of streamlining, efficiency and greater partnership working. In total, 424 Committee conclusions and recommendations (and the government response to them) were analysed.i These are discussed in terms of those inquiries that could be considered as the ‘most’ and ‘least’ influential in terms of subsequent policy impact. In addition, a news media analysis of Committee coverage during the Coalition parliament was also conducted. Taken together, this crude, although acknowledged, way of analysing policy impact provides an initial insight into the committee/department dynamics of 2010-15 and a starting point for more detailed work in this area. In its analysis of Committee influence, this article draws on the work of Colin Hay who differentiated between ‘conduct shaping’ and ‘context shaping’ power. While conduct shaping power is fairly straightforward to measure, context shaping is indirect and can often take on invisible forms. Hay defined such power as ‘the capacity of actors to redefine the parameters of what is socially, politically and economically possible for others’. ii Hay’s concepts, of particular use in a political analysis of this nature, are true to the spirit of, and indeed build upon, Lukes’ influential three dimensions of power, while also incorporating the earlier work of Bachrach and Baratz.iii The Policy Influence of Parliamentary Select Committees Established in 1979, there are approximately 40 Parliamentary Select Committees in the House of Commons, 18 of which shadow government departments (others are established as sub- Committees or undertake work that is more cross-cutting in nature). Select Committees have a wide-ranging remit that involves scrutiny (of the work of their respective departments), monitoring (of policy and legislative developments) and the provision of constructive ideas. Select Committees have traditionally been criticised for being weak and disorganised, with limited ability to influence the policy process. Two major reforms (the Newton Commission and the Wright Reforms) of the past twenty years have, however, seen vast improvements to the committee system. In 2001 the Newton Commission on Parliamentary Scrutiny called for the introduction of core tasks for committees. These included specific roles focused on strategy, policy, expenditure and performance, draft bills, pre- and post-legislative scrutiny and any public appointments 3 associated with their respective departments, along with a clear expectation for increased public engagement. The Commission also called for the publication of regular progress reports to increase committee accountability. While committee membership has always been cross-party, the Wright Reforms of 2010 (established to improve the procedures and relevance of Parliament) introduced the democratic election of all members by secret ballot, a process previously controlled by party Whips. Both reforms have undoubtedly resulted in a more emboldened Committee system that is now routinely associated with exposing government failings and spotlighting forgotten issues. Committees have been encouraged to shape their own agendas by adopting longer-term inquiries that investigate areas of overlooked policy. It is clear that ‘good Parliamentary scrutiny has significant potential to improve the effectiveness of government’iv, and therefore surprising that research into the policy impact of Parliamentary Select Committees is limited. It is important to note that despite improvements to their structure and remit, committees possess restricted authority. While they have the power to call witnesses to attend their hearings and answer questions, they have no powers to block or propose legislation. The government is under no obligation to accept or evaluate any proposals put forward by committees, yet it is obliged to provide a formal, public response within three months of a report’s publication. Powers notwithstanding, committees provide important functions in their role as impartial scrutineers, and are able to provide far more detailed examinations of government policy (or proposed policy) than is possible in Parliamentary debates. Literature on the influence of select committees is contested, with studies painting a mixed picture of ineffectiveness and impact. A large-scale study conducted by Russell and Benton in 2011v provides the most authoritative assessment of the policy influence of seven committees. Russell and Benton found that a large proportion of committee recommendations were neither accepted nor rejected, and that ‘soft’ acceptances or rejections were more common than absolute ones. While the authors found that committee recommendations are influential, they did, however, conclude that fewer than one in ten of the reports produced by committees could be considered as ‘agenda-setting’. Russell and Benton’s findings echo those of Hindmoor et al. vi who, in their study of the Education and Skills Committee, found that while the government rarely rejected recommendations out of hand, it did not openly welcome others. Instead, and in the majority of cases, it claimed to be already addressing the issues the Committee had raised. 4 Ascertaining policy impact is methodologically challenging, and debate relating to the design of appropriate means to assess committee influence continues. It is acknowledged that a basic tick box approach (where the number of government acceptances to committee recommendations are simply counted) is not in itself sufficient to ascertain influence. This approach does, however, provide a good starting point to highlight the particular climate (welcoming, neutral or critical) within which the report was received, and provides a platform from which to conduct further research. It is important to note that official government responses to select committee reports reveal much in themselves. Ministers and Ministerial teams do not wish to highlight their ignorance of a policy problem (or their inactions in dealing with it) given that any such statements are publicly released. As highlighted in previous research, the majority of government responses are therefore vague, non-committal, or provide an assurance that work is already underway. ‘Acceptances’ on paper may not necessarily result in government action, with further inspection required to ascertain the level of subsequent implementation. It is also important to consider ‘delayed influence’ as it is possible that a rejected or ‘shelved’ recommendation will be incorporated it into a future policy idea at a later stage. Research in this area has also highlighted that policy influence can manifest in both direct (conduct shaping) and indirect (context shaping) forms. Direct influence, such as government acceptance of a measurable recommendation, is relatively straightforward to trace. Yet influence can also take on indirect forms, occurring not in the immediate aftermath of a report’s publication, but feeding into the strategies of others (such as sector lobbyists, for example) or influencing subsequent media debate. The ability to influence media debate is an important test of committee impact. While the relationship between media and agenda-setting is not for debate here, it is clear that the greater the levels of coverage, the more likely a committee can hope to influence the wider climate of opinion. Some committees are adept at doing this, mastering the ability to transcend the narrow and un-newsworthy topic of ‘Parliamentary business’ (think Keith Vaz and Home Affairs, Margaret Hodge and the Public Accounts Committee and John Whittingdale and the Culture, Media and Sport Committee, for example). On rare occurrences evidence sessions become news events in themselves (who could forget Rupert Murdoch’s custard pie?). Research conducted by Kubalavii found that while coverage of select committees has risen since the late 1980s, the news media are largely disinterested in Parliamentary business, PMQs notwithstanding. Ensuring that the results of their inquiries are delivered in newsworthy packages should form a key focus for committees. After all, ‘an 5 unreported but authoritative report is likely to be less influential than a similar report which receives wide coverage’viii. Studying the Justice Select Committee The Justice Select Committee is tasked by the House of Commons to provide critical oversight of the work of the Ministry of Justice and the Attorney General’s Office (including their non- departmental agencies and associated public bodies). This wide remit includes the more obvious policy areas of prisons, probation and the courts, but also includes the provision of oversight for the Crown Dependencies, data protection, devolution and constitutional reform. While membership of the Committee changes, it is possible to surmise an understanding of the overarching principles that guide its work. With ‘the strategic objective of raising the quality of debate on justice’, the Committee views its role: ‘… to promote objective and evidence-based debate about criminal justice policy not only within the Committee but also more widely, … we believe that political and media debate needs to pay more attention to what works in reducing crime, rather than assessing that constantly increased spending on longer prison sentences is an unquestionable benefit to society’.ix In common with views expressed by the wider penal reform lobby, the Committee has been critical of the narrow lens through which successive governments have viewed crime reduction - focusing on the Home Office and the Ministry of Justice - while paying less attention to the fields of health and welfare. Through successive reports it continues to stress the importance of greater investment in and uptake of non-custodial options. It has also repeatedly expressed concern about the impact of austerity on the justice system and questioned the government’s evidence base as it oversees widespread cuts to the prison service, the programme of mass court closures and the legal aid budget, for example. Successive Committee reports underline its progressive penal values, drawing parallels with the group of elite experts, including politicians, who worked to develop liberal penal policy in the post-war period. Indeed, the Committee’s aim to create ‘a ‘safe space’ in which to foster rational and fundamental debate on justice policy’x is reminiscent of this ‘golden era’ model. Despite such parallels, it is important to note that the Committee does not operate in an idealised, post-war penal utopia. A great many of its reports demonstrate its understanding that 6 the justice system must modernise, streamline and make efficiency savings where appropriate. Indeed, prior to the implementation of Transforming Rehabilitation, the Committee expressed interest in the greater use of privatisation in the penal field. While it is not possible to state that the Committee is somehow ‘different’ from other parliamentary select committees, the provision of an ideological ‘mission statement’ provides a clear symbolic marker in this populist policy terrain. The Committee produced 56 publications during the Coalition parliament (in addition to a large amount of other material including letters and responses to consultations), all of which attempted to influence the penal agenda. While not reviewing every publication, this article focuses on fifteen inquiries highlighted by the Committee as important.xi Some of the inquiries were proactive (following a scandal or pressure from campaigners or constituents), while others were more reactive in nature, reviewing government policy or providing post-legislative scrutiny, for example. Many of the inquiries fell under the broad title ‘transforming justice’, including major reports on the probation service, women offenders, older prisoners, crime reduction policies, prisons planning and policy, developments in family courts and reforms to the legal aid budget. It is important to note that other the inquiries reviewed, while not directly falling under the same agenda, were also conducted during a period of unprecedented cuts to the justice budget. They included inquiries on the Freedom of Information Act, EU proposals for data protection, the Capita interpreter contract, the doctrine of Joint Enterprise, the legal situation in relation to missing persons and the presumption of death, the impact of legal aid reforms on mesothelioma claims, manorial rights and the Crown Dependencies of Jersey and Guernsey. Policy Influence The Department outright accepted 68 (16%) of the Committee’s 424 conclusions or recommendations. It implicitly or partially accepted 51 (12%), neither accepted or rejected 134 (32%), implicitly rejected 71 (17%) and outright rejected 51 (12%). It failed to respond (in any form) to 49 (12%). Outright rejections - along the lines of ‘the government rejects’ - were fewer in number than implicit rejections where it was clear that the government disagreed, but had avoided providing a hostile response. Although challenging to gauge whether such results constituted effective work on the part of the Committee (as there is nothing to compare it to), it is interesting to note that the findings are broadly consistent with Russell and Benton’s 7 analysis of the Home Affairs Select Committee during the 1997-2010 period (which until 2007 included the justice brief). Given the space constraints of this article, only certain inquiries are discussed here. These include an analysis of those considered to be most and least influential, along with a synopsis of the coverage they received in the national print media. Four out of the fifteen reports could be considered as conduct shaping, resulting in action from the government in the form of a further review or the publication of draft legislation. Research was conducted to qualify the nature of any government action taken, although this was only possible where the Committee’s recommendation was measurable. Most Influential: Joint Enterprise, Presumption of Death, Women Offenders and Mesothelioma The below examples demonstrated the Committee’s clear ‘conduct shaping’ credentials: pressuring the government to publish new policy guidance, kick-starting a sluggish policy agenda and delaying controversial plans. These different forms of influence are to be commended and illustrated the important work that the Committee undertook. It was regretful, therefore, to uncover a number of wasted opportunities where the government provided short- term action that did not result in longer-term change. The Committee’s inquiry into the common law doctrine of joint enterprise in 2012 was prompted by concerns expressed by campaigners and victim’s groups. The doctrine, a form of secondary liability, is often used in murder cases, and allows more than one person to be charged and convicted of the same crime without requiring proof of a direct involvement. The Committee received evidence from a range of parties who highlighted its inconsistent application, disproportionate use against young persons and complexity for juries. In its final report, the Committee called for the enshrinement of the joint enterprise doctrine in statute to ensure better clarity for all involved in the criminal justice system, the creation of clear guidelines for prosecutors and greater clarity of the number of people charged under the doctrine each year. Of its six conclusions and recommendations, the government accepted two, rejected one, and ignored three. While it refused to consult on the new legislation proposed by the Committee, it accepted the recommendation for the Director of Public Prosecutions to create guidelines for prosecutors on handling joint enterprise cases and promised that the CPS would look to collect data on the number of joint enterprise cases in future (a number previously unknown). New guidelines were duly published, and data on the number of cases involving 8 joint enterprise were published by the CPS in 2012 and 2013. The CPS has not, however, published updated figures since this date. The inquiry into the presumption of death in 2012 was another proactive endeavour. The Committee was prompted to investigate the situation following correspondence from constituents (an issue growing in prominence following media coverage of the high-profile disappearance of Claudia Lawrence in 2009). Receiving evidence from a wide-range of campaign groups and activists, the inquiry concluded that families of missing persons suffered not only emotionally and financially, but also from a ‘legislative patchwork of bewildering complexity’ and an unacceptable lack of information from authorities (including police, lawyers and financial institutions). The government accepted seven of the Committee’s ten conclusions and recommendations and duly published better guidance to help families navigate the law. The Committee also called for two legislative changes; first to allow families to obtain a certificate of presumed death, and second to create the legal status of ‘guardian of the affairs of a missing person’. Both recommendations are now enshrined in law (The Presumption of Death Act 2013 and, following a government consultation, the Guardianship (Missing Persons) Act 2017), although it is important to note that both Acts started as a Private Members Bills and not legislation originally put forward by the government. The women offenders inquiry of 2013 sought to review progress five years after the publication of the Corston Report (a government-sponsored inquiry into the particular vulnerabilities of women in prison). Another proactive project, the Committee critiqued government progress on women’s penal policy which had virtually disappeared from the policy agenda following a sustained period of Ministerial focus during the final years of New Labour. Among its thirty- three recommendations and conclusions, the Committee called for more visible Ministerial leadership and the publication of an immediate strategy for progress. The government accepted (or implicitly/partially accepted) sixteen out of the Committees thirty-three conclusions and recommendations. However, its largely defensive response refuted the Committee’s conclusions that it treated women in the penal system as an ‘afterthought’, and disagreed with the Committee’s recommendation that it should commission women’s services separately in future. The government made no commitments to protect the extremely popular network of women’s community centres (utilised by many women serving community sentences) once they were moved to the control of private offender management companies in 2015, arguing that market forces would determine their future. 9 Disagreements notwithstanding, the inquiry undoubtedly refocused government thinking on this issue with action commencing during the inquiry itself. Tangible progress came in the form of the publication of a six-page strategy document outlining government visions for women in the criminal justice system. Responding to the Committee’s criticism that it did not consider women’s penal policy as a priority, the government promised to publish yearly progress reports, although this occurred just once in 2014. In addition to the publication of the strategy, the Ministry of Justice established a high-level advisory board which included membership from key stakeholders in the women’s penal field. While its first leader, Justice Minister Helen Grant, was not in post for long, the advisory board has weathered the Ministerial merry-go- round to keep women’s penal policy on the political agenda. Changes in the penal field notwithstanding, the Committee’s inquiry certainly revived this stagnant policy area to ensure a renewed focus on women, although it is regretful that no ‘updates’ have been published since 2014 with the current Ministerial focus hard to ascertain. The Committee’s inquiry into mesothelioma claims in 2014 was prompted by the Government’s decision to apply sections 44 and 46 of Legal Aid, Sentencing and Punishment of Offenders (LASPO) Act 2014 to mesothelioma claims as well as other personal injury claims. The planned effect of these sections was to remove the capacity of successful claimants to recover certain costs from the losing party. This was particularly contentious in the case of mesothelioma, a disease caused by exposure to asbestos. The Committee concluded that the government’s review of mesothelioma claims (the consultation prior to its decision to apply LASPO reforms to such cases) was not prepared in a thorough manner and recommended that that it commission a further independent review of the risks involved. Crucially, the government’s response to the Committee was delayed due to a judicial review on the matter. Consistent with the views expressed by the Committee, the High Court overturned the government’s decision and ruled that mesothelioma claims should operate on a pre-LASPO basis. While the government did not explicitly act on any of the recommendations made by the Committee, it is clear that its inquiry, in conjunction with the judicial review, ensured that the government halted its plans. Keen to demonstrate its commitment to mesothelioma sufferers, however, the government went on to introduce new reforms in the Mesothelioma Act 2014. Least Influential: Manorial Rights, Legal Aid and Crime Reduction Policies The Committee had less influence following those inquiries that the government considered to be too niche or where it called for a pause or re-think of the overarching penal agenda. On 10 several occasions the Committee was informed that it would not be cost-effective to implement its recommendations (or that they were simply not a priority); the government also refused to pause to reconsider its most contentious policy proposals. The Committee’s inquiry into manorial rights (rights which are retained by lords of the manner when the land became freehold, including sporting, hunting and fishing rights and the right to hold markets) in 2015 was prompted by the coming into effect of new provisions in the Land Registration Act 2002 which required landowners to claim their rights to land by virtue of a register. The deadline in 2013 prompted 9,000 registrations and resulted in thousands of unsuspecting homeowners having claims made on their land or properties. The Committee received many representations which called for the abolition of manorial rights (viewed as a feudal throwback) or a review of the law in this area. The Committee refused to take a stance, but instead recommended that the Law Commission should undertake research to ascertain whether the law relating to manorial rights should be abolished or retained, and whether legislation could address any compensation rights if it was amended. The government did not recognise the issues raised by the inquiry as causing a significant issue, and while thanking the inquiry for investigating, viewed further research or a fundamental review of manorial rights as ‘disproportionate’. In a time of scarce resources, the government made clear that its main focus was on the implementation of the Transforming Rehabilitation agenda. The conclusions of those inquires that fell under this banner received a relatively high level of resistance from government. In 2011 the Committee undertook pre-legislative scrutiny of the government’s proposed reform of legal aid. The government claimed that it was putting a much-needed end to the ‘compensation culture’ and that the reforms would result in greater effectiveness and efficiency. The Committee called on the government to assess more fully the likely impact of the reforms on litigants as well as public expenditure before it embarked on implementation. Of the thirty-four conclusions and recommendations, the government outright accepted just one, and rejected (implicitly or explicitly) seventeen. It stated that a large proportion of recommendations or conclusions (fifteen) were already being worked on independently to the Committee’s inquiry. Demonstrating its intention to press ahead with the agenda and ignore the Committee’s recommendations, the government published a draft format of the Legal Aid, Sentencing and Punishment of Offenders Bill on the same day as its official response to the Committee. It was clear that despite the Committee’s requirement to undertake pre-legislative scrutiny, the government would not be halted in its tracks. 11 The report with the highest number of outright or implicit rejections (32 out of 55) was the Crime Reduction Policies inquiry of 2014. It represented, in many respects, an early audit of the Coalition government’s proposals for Transforming Justice (assessing the government’s approach to cutting crime, including the areas of governance and contract management, community safety, prisons and probation). Among its wide-ranging recommendations, the Committee called on the government to implement better measures to understand variances in re-offending rates, to rectify prison overcrowding, to provide an adequate assessment of the risks involved in implementing the Transforming Rehabilitation reforms and to establish an independent and authoritative body to evaluate the effectiveness of its crime reduction policies. The government’s response to this major piece of work by the Committee (encompassing two separate reports) was largely negative, and did not reflect the conciliatory nature of most other responses. Its defensive tone signalled that while it was perhaps willing to make small-scale policy amendments following niche inquiries, it was not in the business of accepting Committee criticism in relation to more fundamental policy transformations. Influencing the Media Agenda? While crime and punishment is a constituent part of the daily news diet, coverage of the Justice Select Committee pales in comparison. A comprehensive news media analysis demonstrates that between 2010 and 2015, the Committee’s inquiries (all 56) were referenced 114 times in national UK newspapers. Of this figure, 67 articles were directly influenced by a report’s publication (referenced in the headline or providing the main content of the article, for example). This is somewhat unexpected considering the newsworthy and often contentious subjects that the Committee investigates. It is also comparatively less than coverage received by the Home Affairs Select Committee during the 1997-2010 period (which received an average of 17 report-related articles per year versus the 13 received by the Justice Select Committee).xii The majority of coverage highlighted the Committee’s headline findings that were the most critical of government. It is perhaps therefore unsurprising that the greatest levels of coverage were in the left-leaning quality press.xiii Such newspapers – with a long interest in social justice issues – were able to use the Committee’s critical reports to attack the government’s penal record. It is regrettable, therefore, that they also failed to follow up on some of the government’s inactions. 12 The inquiry into joint enterprise was by far the most newsworthy in the sample, mentioned in twenty-seven media articles spanning 2012-2015; the longest coverage from any single inquiry. Most articles referred to individual case studies which highlighted the doctrine’s unfair or inconsistent application. The inquiry into probation was mentioned twelve times, with articles focusing on cuts to the probation budget (which were putting safety on the line) and the increasing levels of red-tape faced by probation officers. Articles covering the prison inquiry (nine in total) similarly focused on cuts to the justice budget and its impact on levels of self- harm and suicide on the custodial estate. The inquiry into the Capita interpreter contract garnered particularly hostile coverage towards the government, with the actions of the Ministry of Justice deemed as shambolic, and costing the taxpayer millions of pounds. The women offenders inquiry also received less coverage than expected (covered in just seven newspaper articles), an unexpected situation given the newsworthiness attributed to female lawbreakers. Finally, given the newsworthy nature of (and previously uncovered) issues covered in the presumption of death inquiry, it is noteworthy that the report received limited coverage, with only five news articles dedicated to its publication. The rules of newsworthiness dictate that unless committees are dealing in controversial issues they are likely to be overlooked by the media. Yet here presents the conundrum. The Justice Select Committee oversees a department which is tasked with one of the most contentious policy briefs in government. Indeed, nothing gets the right-leaning press in more of a spin than the government’s perceived inactions on law and order. Yet empirical analysis reveals that Justice Committee business was of almost no interest to such publications (and of relatively little interest to left-leaning publications also). It is recognised, once again, that while the subject of crime has unparalleled newsworthiness, the development or indeed scrutiny of crime policy does not. Much like the department whose work it oversees, the Justice Select Committee cannot expect to automatically receive media coverage, despite its institutional advantage. And so while the ability to shape the context of media coverage remains an important part of this picture, it makes sense for the Committee to pursue more direct forms of political influence. Influencing the Penal Agenda? Reviewing approximately one third of the Committee’s output during the 2010-2015 Parliament, this article does not attempt to make substantive conclusions about the overall level of policy influence that it was able to exert. It is, however, fair to say that the Committee was 13 unable to exert influence in every inquiry reviewed, and the results of this research are therefore consistent with those of Russell and Benton, who stated that fewer than 10% of committee reports could be considered as agenda-setting. A major critique relates to the wording of Committee recommendations (asking for specific action) and conclusions (stating an opinion). The combination of recommendations and conclusions in long, single paragraphs made it challenging to ascertain what specific action the Committee desired, and allowed the government - in a vast number of cases - to dodge the key point/s. Recommendations were far fewer than conclusions, and given the fact that the government was under no obligation to respond to each point, this felt like a wasted opportunity. While the number of outright rejections to recommendations and conclusions was low, their vague wording paved way for a large number of equally vague ‘non-responses’, indifference or provision the official line. Furthermore, the limited measurability of the Committee’s recommendations meant that there was no clear way to trace whether the government had acted upon them or not. Critique notwithstanding, it is clear that the Committee did have traceable ‘conduct shaping’ impact in a number of areas. In the fields of joint enterprise and the presumption of death, the Committee persuaded the government of the need to introduce new guidelines and legislative reforms. The women offenders inquiry kick-started government action and led to the publication of an official strategy as well as the establishment of a Ministerial working group. These proactive inquiries, undertaken following concerns raised by campaigners, can be viewed as agenda-setting. The longevity or continuation of such influence must be questioned, however, when considering how long the by government ‘honoured’ its promises, a situation exacerbated by the Ministerial merry-go-round in the Ministry of Justice. While there is evidence of sustained action in some cases (such as the publication of guidance still accessible via the internet), other action was short-term despite promises to the contrary. The Committee often fell victim to short-term ‘sweeteners’ and its influence must be measured in terms of its ability to apply long-term pressure. It is clear that more follow-up work in the form of correspondence or inquiries (which it often undertakes) is required. The Committee exerted less impact following those inquiries that were considered to be too niche (with the government refusing to commit resources) or too critical of the government’s own agenda. The government responses to inquiries conducted towards the end of the Parliament (encompassing the topics of crime reduction and prison policy, for example) were 14 certainly more political in nature and framed in the new rhetoric of Transforming Rehabilitation. These more combative and dismissive responses brought into question the ability of the Committee to engage in ‘context shaping’ in relation to the most significant justice transformations. One could question whether the Committee was deliberately undercut in such instances (on the grounds that ideas were against the dominant ideology or that ‘government knows best’), or whether government preparedness to act on recommendations was influenced by its commitment to austerity. It seems that the answer is, unsurprisingly, a mixture of both. In its responses to the Committee, the government routinely mentioned its desire to cut unnecessary spending (in the case of the legal aid budget, for example), but it was also clear that it paid little attention to Committee findings on many occasions (rejecting conclusions while signalling its intention to press ahead with its policy and legislative agenda). Conclusion As this article has demonstrated, conduct shaping is a key part of political influence. But, as argued by Hay, it cannot alone provide the complete picture of power dynamics. The related, although less powerful, concept of advocacy (the championing or promotion of a particular issue) must also be considered in this context. While both are important components of the ‘influence’ equation, one holds more immediate and observable agenda-setting potential. Considering such concepts in relation to the work of the Justice Select Committee – for the very first time - is therefore a useful endeavour. The conclusions of this research reveal that the Committee was most effective in conduct shaping as a result of its smaller, proactive inquiries. It failed, however, to exert context shaping power in relation to the government’s overarching penal agenda, where critical comments were largely met with resistance. Such findings highlight that in this era of new penal governance the Justice Select Committee is just one player in a growing policy network. While it is certainly able to exert forms of political power not available to others (including the ability to exert ‘soft’ power), the government is now accountable to a vast array of service providers who are contracted to administer the penal landscape on its behalf. The Committee must remain robust. As a key network player its attempts to influence or, in the words of Hay, ‘refine the parameters’ of penal policy (one of its key stated objectives) must continue, of crucial importance in this populist policy sphere. Small-scale changes, including greater clarity of the observable government action that it requires along with a capacity to monitor long-term progress, would undoubtedly improve this endeavour. 15 i Responses were coded as: accept, partially/implicitly accept, neither accept or reject (including already underway), partially/implicitly reject/non-answer or reject. ii Hay, C. (2002) Political Analysis: A Critical Introduction Basingstoke: Palgrave, p185. iii For classic discussions of the role of power in the political process see Bachrach, P. and Baratz, M. (1962) ‘Two Faces of Power’ The American Political Science Review 56:4 947- 952, and Lukes, S. (2004) Power: A Radical View Basingstoke: Palgrave iv Institute for Government (2015) Select Committees under Scrutiny: The Impact of Parliamentary Committee Inquiries on Government London: Institute for Government. v Russell, M. and Benton, M. (2011) Selective Influence: The Policy Impact of House of Commons Select Committees. The Constitution Unit: UCL. See also Russell, M. and Benton, M. (2013) ‘Assessing the Impact of Parliamentary Oversight Committees: The Select Committees in the British House of Commons’ Parliamentary Affairs 66:4 772-797 vi Hindmoor, A., Larkin, P. and Kennon, A. (2009) ‘Assessing the Influence of Select Committees in the UK: The Education and Skills Committee, 1997–2005’ Journal of Legislative Studies 15:1 71-89. vii Kubala, M. (2011) ‘Select Committees in the House of Commons and the Media’ Parliamentary Affairs 64:4 694-713. viii Natzler, D. and Hutton, M. (2005) ‘Select Committees: Scrutiny a La Carte?’ in P. Giddings (ed.) The Future of Parliament Basingstoke: Palgrave, p97. ix House of Commons Justice Committee (2015) The work of the Committee in the 2010-15 Parliament. Tenth Report of Session 2014-15. HC 1123 x House of Commons Justice Committee (2015) The work of the Committee in the 2010-15 Parliament. Tenth Report of Session 2014-15. HC 1123 xi As above. xii Russell, M. and Benton, M. (2011) Selective Influence: The Policy Impact of House of Commons Select Committees. The Constitution Unit: UCL, p39. xiii The Independent dedicated the most amount of coverage to Committee reports (38 articles), followed by the Guardian/Observer (27). The right-leaning Telegraph had nineteen articles, the Daily Mail eight and the Times seven. work_4rarknin3vbppnka3u53rxr3lm ---- societies Article Victims, Criminal Justice and State Compensation David Miers Emeritus Professor of Law, School of Law and Politics, Cardiff University, Cardiff CF10 2AS, UK; davidmiers2@gmail.com Received: 22 February 2019; Accepted: 17 April 2019; Published: 24 April 2019 ���������� ������� Abstract: This article examines one element of the state’s responses to crime: the provision of a taxpayer-funded compensation scheme for victims of personal and sexual violence. The Criminal Injuries Compensation Scheme 2012 sits within a political context that seeks to ensure that victims of crime are better served by the criminal justice system of England and Wales, the jurisdiction that is the focus of this article. The government’s fundamental policy is that this scheme exists to compensate only those victims who are ‘blameless’, either in terms of their character, criminal record, conduct at the time of the incident, or in their engagement with the criminal justice agencies. It is a policy that illuminates elements of two of the questions that the editors posed for this Special Issue of Societies. Reviewing the increased urgency in government policies concerning the treatment of victims of crime, the first section addresses the question of how, why and when victims came to shape political and criminal justice discourse and practice. The question of how, and to what end, cultural representations have shaped perceptions of victims is addressed in the second and third sections, which examine the notion of victim status and illustrate the ways in which eligible (‘ideal’) victims are perceived and their claims under this scheme are determined. Keywords: victims of crime; ideal victims; criminal justice; state compensation 1. Victims and the Criminal Justice System In any analysis of the criminal justice system (CJS) of England and Wales (but also of almost all other common-law Western systems),1 it has been a commonplace to remark on what some have described as ‘the rediscovery’ [1] (pp. 5–10), the ‘rebirth’ [2] (pp. 69–94), [3] (pp. 7–19), or the ‘re-emergence’ of the victim [4] (pp. 26–28) over the past 50 years, in contrast to their marginalised role as a third party to the criminal trial [5,6]. In truth, while their historical relationship with the CJS might have been more pronounced, victims had never gone away. Even as the state assumed a near-monopoly during the 19th century over the detection, detention, prosecution and disposal of those who break the criminal law [7] (pp. 127–158), victims played a legitimising role, at least in the sense that the unlawful infringement of their personal autonomy warranted state condemnation via the criminal trial. As these and other analyses have documented, this did not carry with it a corresponding stake in the outcome of the trial. Here the victim’s principal role was to give evidence in support of the Crown. Victims were little more than witnesses to the incident in which they were injured or their property stolen from them, and were, for the most part, subject to the same rules governing cross-examination by the defendant as was any other witness; conditions that, with the exception of child and rape victims, continue to apply. As third parties, they had no right to put their own case for recognition of the injuries or losses they had sustained, or for possible redress, as had been the case, notably, by 1 ‘CJS’ is the standard abbreviation used by the Ministry of Justice. Societies 2019, 9, 29; doi:10.3390/soc9020029 www.mdpi.com/journal/societies http://www.mdpi.com/journal/societies http://www.mdpi.com http://dx.doi.org/10.3390/soc9020029 http://www.mdpi.com/journal/societies https://www.mdpi.com/2075-4698/9/2/29?type=check_update&version=2 Societies 2019, 9, 29 2 of 13 means of prosecution for reward [8] (chs. 3–6). Any judicial satisfaction of these concerns became a matter for the victim’s civil action against the offender. As is also well documented, the government has, over the past half-century, made substantial changes to the relationship between victims of crime and the CJS. This victim focus gained traction as a predominantly state-led response to the collapse of the rehabilitative ideal [9] (pp. 9–10) and was designed to lead to what the government characterised as a ‘rebalancing’ of criminal justice policy in favour of the victim’s interests [10]. No longer marginalised, ‘the rising visibility of the victim’ in the 1960s and 1970s’ [11] (p. 24) [12] recast that relationship in a number of ways, intended to ‘make sure that the victim’s voice is heard at the heart of Government’ [13] (p. 8). This is a claim that for many critics remains unfulfilled, but which in practice presents a number of challenges to an even-handed criminal justice system [14,15]. These ideological concerns were coupled with an instrumental recognition that as gatekeepers to the CJS, victims’ willingness or otherwise to engage with it by reporting crime and supporting a prosecution is likely to be influenced by their perception of the extent to which the system both recognises their injuries and reliably produces the outcomes they reasonably expect. Those outcomes are ‘that offenders are caught, that they are punished, and that they are dealt with in a way that reduces the likelihood of their re-offending and creating more victims’ [16] (p. 8). These changes also implied an increasing degree of inclusiveness in which victims have, in a further extension of the marketplace analysis of the CJS, become consumers of its services [17] (pp. 24–25). Like the consumers of health care, financial, local authorities or legal services, victims of crime now have their own complaints procedures where the criminal justice agencies fail to deliver on their ‘key entitlements’ to be informed about the progress and the outcomes of those agencies’ decisions. First published in 1990 as the Victims’ Charter, these entitlements are detailed in the current Code of Practice for Victims of Crime (Victims’ Code) [18], restated in 2015 to give effect to Article 14 of the 2012 Victims Directive.2 However, it should be recognised that while the Victims’ Code comprises a formal recognition of the state’s obligations to engage with them and to provide for their security [19,20], its entitlements also carry with them a mutual obligation to engage with the CJS. Thus, victims of crime may, variously, and at different stages in the CJS, be characterised as: • both suppliers (e.g., to the police about an offence against them) and recipients of information (e.g., from the police concerning their response to that report); • partners in crime prevention (e.g., in target-hardening their homes, or taking personal safety measures); • the beneficiaries of remedial arrangements (e.g., concerning such matters as the giving of evidence in rape trials, or of the availability of state-funded, and where they are convicted, of offender compensation); and • as participants in the system (e.g., in particular via restorative justice). Modern concepts of social citizenship assert that where the state supports their rights to health and welfare provision, citizens have a corresponding responsibility to take care of their bodily (e.g., to keep fit and not to smoke) and economic (e.g., to seek employment) well-being, as conditions for their access to that provision [21,22]. In the same way, victims of crime may be said to have responsibilities to the CJS that correspond to their access to its entitlements [23] [24] (p. 57). As a judge of the Upper Tribunal put the matter when dealing with paragraph 23 of the Criminal Injuries Compensation Scheme 2012 (CICS 2012), which provides that an award will be withheld unless the applicant has cooperated as far as reasonably practicable in bringing the assailant to justice, ‘a person who seeks compensation from 2 Directive 2012/29/EU of the European Parliament and of the Council of 25 October 2012 establishing minimum standards on the rights, support and protection of victims of crime, and replacing Council Framework Decision 2001/220/JHA [2012] OJ L315. Societies 2019, 9, 29 3 of 13 the State in respect of a criminal injury ought, as a quid pro quo, to assist the State to prosecute the offender insofar as that may be appropriate’.3 The legislation that authorised the Victims’ Code also established the Victims’ Commissioner,4 whose role is to promote the interests of victims and witnesses and to encourage good practice in their treatment by the CJS. The implementation of victims’ entitlements under the Victims’ Code, which the Commissioner also regularly reviews, engages the full range of the CJS’s actors. It identifies 14 ‘service providers’, of whom the police, the Crown Prosecution Service (CPS), HM Courts and Tribunals Service, the National Probation Service and the Parole Board are some of the principals. In addition to these various initiatives, there have been important changes in substantive and adjectival law designed to secure more convictions by directly or indirectly addressing victims’ concerns, in particular in connection with their place in the criminal trial [25] (pp. 116–190). More recent changes include strengthened statutory duties on sentencing courts to order offenders to compensate their victims,5 and a new non-statutory procedure by which victims can challenge decisions by the CPS not to prosecute in their case.6 These changes are not uncontroversial, typically presenting normative and ideological tensions between the public and the private interest in what the state and the victim recognise as criminal ‘justice’. These tensions are illustrated, for example, by the continuing controversy concerning reform of the evidential rules governing the cross-examination of both adult and child victims of sexual offences,7 the CPS’ failure to disclose unused evidence of relevance to the defence [27], and individual victims’ concerns about what they perceive as the ‘injustice’ of potentially lenient sentences in their own cases.8 The success of these developments and the expectations that they have encouraged have faced two criticisms. The first is that while victims may, in other contexts, seek a judicial review of these service providers’ decisions,9 none of the entitlements in the Victims’ Code is of itself legally enforceable. Where they ‘feel’ that their ‘entitlements have not been met or that any service provider has not delivered their duties under the Code’, a victim may make a formal complaint to that provider. However, the provider’s response does not carry with it an obligation to take any further action or to provide any other redress. In its first review of service providers’ compliance with the complaints procedure, the Victims’ Commissioner found that most of the victims interviewed said they had not been made aware 3 R (RW) v First-tier Tribunal (as successor of the Criminal Injuries Compensation Appeals Panel) [2013] AACR 8 [24] (Judge Rowland). 4 https://victimscommissioner.org.uk/. The Domestic Violence, Crime and Victims Act 2004 also established a Victims’ Advisory Panel for victims of crime and their families to have a say in the reform of the CJS. This was abolished in 2013 (The Public Bodies (Abolition of Victims’ Advisory Panel) Order 2013, 2013 No. 2853) but re-established as the Victims’ Panel with effect from 6 February 2017; Hansard, House of Commons, Written question 64616, Victims’ Panel, answered 27 February 2017 (Dr Philip Lee MP, Ministry of Justice); see also https://www.gov.uk/government/news/criminals-paying-more-than-ever-to- help-victims. 5 Section 130(2A) and (3) the Powers of Criminal Courts (Sentencing) Act 2000 now require a sentencing court to consider whether to make a compensation order when it has power to do so, and to give reasons where it does not do so. 6 Crown Prosecution Service, Reconsidering a Prosecution Decision, taking effect from June 2013; https://www.cps.gov.uk/legal- guidance/reconsidering-prosecution-decision. The CPS’ Victims’ Right to Review Scheme was introduced to give effect to Article 11 of the Victims’ Directive; it also responds to the Court of Appeal’s criticisms in Christopher Killick [2011] EWCA Crim 1608; and see R v DPP and Boyling [2018] EWHC 3508 (Admin). 7 Crown Prosecution Service, Special Measures; https://www.cps.gov.uk/legal-guidance/special-measures [26]. Similar criticism has been levelled at the current rules permitting personal cross-examination by the alleged abuser in family court proceedings concerning domestic abuse, currently being addressed in HM Government, Transforming the Response to Domestic Abuse: Consultation Response and Draft Bill (CP 15, January 2019). 8 Crown Prosecution Service, Unduly Lenient Sentences; https://www.cps.gov.uk/legal-guidance/unduly-lenient-sentences. 9 For example, the decision by the Parole Board where it was considering an offender’s early release from prison, R (DSD and NBV) v The Parole Board of England and Wales [2018] EWHC 694 (Admin) (John Worboys). Responding to this decision, the government is to introduce a new mechanism by which victims who believe a decision may be fundamentally flawed will be able to make a case for reconsideration by Ministry of Justice official, rather than having to resort to the courts and engage legal representation to argue their case; House of Commons Debates, vol 654, ws cols 5–6, (4 February 2019); https://hansard. parliament.uk/commons/2019-02-04/debates/19020414000011/ParoleBoardReconsiderationMechanismAndRulesReview. https://victimscommissioner.org.uk/ https://www.gov.uk/government/news/criminals-paying-more-than-ever-to-help-victims https://www.gov.uk/government/news/criminals-paying-more-than-ever-to-help-victims https://www.cps.gov.uk/legal-guidance/reconsidering-prosecution-decision https://www.cps.gov.uk/legal-guidance/reconsidering-prosecution-decision https://www.cps.gov.uk/legal-guidance/special-measures https://www.cps.gov.uk/legal-guidance/unduly-lenient-sentences https://hansard.parliament.uk/commons/2019-02-04/debates/19020414000011/ParoleBoardReconsiderationMechanismAndRulesReview https://hansard.parliament.uk/commons/2019-02-04/debates/19020414000011/ParoleBoardReconsiderationMechanismAndRulesReview Societies 2019, 9, 29 4 of 13 of the Victims’ Code or of their entitlements, and did not know what to do if they had concerns. Almost three quarters of those who had complained were unhappy with the response that they received.10 The second criticism, also illustrated by research conducted by the Victims’ Commissioner, is that the implementation of such other initiatives as offering victims the opportunity to engage in restorative justice with their offenders, and on offering them the opportunity to make a Victim Personal Statement when the court is considering its sentence on their offender, has been patchy.11 Against the background of increasing rates of recorded sexual offences and of crimes of violence against the person involving knives,12 the terms of reference for the Ministry of Justice’s review of CICS 2012 asserts that ‘compensation is an important part of government provision of end-to-end support for victims of violent crime’.13 However, there has been growing criticism that when dealing with their claims, the Criminal Injuries Compensation Authority (CICA), the statutory agency responsible for dealing with applications made under CICS 2012, is failing to recognise the impact of the offence on the victim. The Victims’ Commissioner ’s Review of the scheme, published in January 2019, found that the interviewed victims felt validated when the impact of the crime had been recognised by society in the form of an award of compensation, but the process of making their claim was often traumatic: ‘we have an overly complex transactional process, which pays insufficient regard to the complex needs of its users, many of whom are likely to be suffering from the effects of trauma.’14 Responding to what were, by 2015, long-standing criticisms, the Conservative Government indicated that it would bring forward measures ‘to increase the rights of victims of crime’, which would ‘build on the existing Victims’ Code to guarantee greater protections for victims and witnesses in the CJS, including that victims of crime have the right to make a Victim Personal Statement and read it out in court at sentencing and at the Parole Board.’15 No such measures were introduced, but in 2018, the government published its cross-departmental Victims Strategy, whose overarching aims are to consolidate the reforms that have been made and to strengthen them ‘to ensure victims have the right help in the aftermath of a crime and are properly supported in the process of seeing justice delivered’ [29] (p. 8). There are many specific proposals, notably ‘to introduce new guidance for criminal justice agencies to provide practical advice to assist when explaining the Victim Personal Statement process to victims’. Of potentially greater significance for the implementation of the Victims’ Code is the government’s proposed consultation on a Victims’ Law, which will address the procedural limitations to making sure that victims receive the services to which they are entitled, and to holding criminal justice agencies that fail to deliver them to account. 2. The Social Construction of Victims of Crime ‘What does it mean to be a victim? Why is it this status is conferred on some and denied to others?’ [30] (p. 45). Positivist victimology had sought to explain victimisation by an examination of those held (typically by formal criminal justice processes) to be victims, in particular by a concentration 10 Victims’ Commissioner, A Review of Complaints and Resolution for Victims of Crime (2015) p. 5; https://s3-eu-west-2.amazonaws. com/victimscomm-prod-storage-clhgxgum05k1/uploads/2015/01/A-Review-of-Complaints-and-Resolution-for-Victims-of- Crime_January20151.pdf. 11 On victim personal statements (alternatively called victim impact statements [28], see Victims’ Commissioner, Victim Personal Statements 2017/18 (2018); https://s3-eu-west-2.amazonaws.com/victimscomm-prod-storage-clhgxgum05k1/uploads/2018/10/ VPS-slide-pack-2017-18-FINAL.pdf; and on restorative justice, Victims’ Commissioner, A Question of Quality: A Review of Restorative Justice, Part 2—Victims (2016); https://s3-eu-west-2.amazonaws.com/victimscomm-prod-storage-clhgxgum05k1/ uploads/2016/11/VC-review-into-restorative-justice-services-part-2_November-2016.pdf. 12 Some of these increases are attributable to better recording; otherwise, there has been ‘no change in overall violent offences estimated by the CSEW (1,389,000). Office for National Statistics, https://www.ons.gov.uk/peoplepopulationandcommunity/ crimeandjustice/bulletins/crimeinenglandandwales/yearendingseptember2018; Sections 2 and 6. 13 http://data.parliament.uk/DepositedPapers/Files/DEP2018-1283/terms_of_reference_CICS_Review.pdf. 14 Compensation without re-traumatisation (2019); https://s3-eu-west-2.amazonaws.com/victimscomm-prod-storage- clhgxgum05k1/uploads/2019/01/CIC-report-FINAL.pdf, p. 97. 15 Queen’s Speech 2015: Background Briefing Notes; https://assets.publishing.service.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/ attachment_data/file/430149/QS_lobby_pack_FINAL_NEW_2.pdf#page=94. https://s3-eu-west-2.amazonaws.com/victimscomm-prod-storage-clhgxgum05k1/uploads/2015/01/A-Review-of-Complaints-and-Resolution-for-Victims-of-Crime_January20151.pdf https://s3-eu-west-2.amazonaws.com/victimscomm-prod-storage-clhgxgum05k1/uploads/2015/01/A-Review-of-Complaints-and-Resolution-for-Victims-of-Crime_January20151.pdf https://s3-eu-west-2.amazonaws.com/victimscomm-prod-storage-clhgxgum05k1/uploads/2015/01/A-Review-of-Complaints-and-Resolution-for-Victims-of-Crime_January20151.pdf https://s3-eu-west-2.amazonaws.com/victimscomm-prod-storage-clhgxgum05k1/uploads/2018/10/VPS-slide-pack-2017-18-FINAL.pdf https://s3-eu-west-2.amazonaws.com/victimscomm-prod-storage-clhgxgum05k1/uploads/2018/10/VPS-slide-pack-2017-18-FINAL.pdf https://s3-eu-west-2.amazonaws.com/victimscomm-prod-storage-clhgxgum05k1/uploads/2016/11/VC-review-into-restorative-justice-services-part-2_November-2016.pdf https://s3-eu-west-2.amazonaws.com/victimscomm-prod-storage-clhgxgum05k1/uploads/2016/11/VC-review-into-restorative-justice-services-part-2_November-2016.pdf https://www.ons.gov.uk/peoplepopulationandcommunity/crimeandjustice/bulletins/crimeinenglandandwales/yearendingseptember2018 https://www.ons.gov.uk/peoplepopulationandcommunity/crimeandjustice/bulletins/crimeinenglandandwales/yearendingseptember2018 http://data.parliament.uk/DepositedPapers/Files/DEP2018-1283/terms_of_reference_CICS_Review.pdf https://s3-eu-west-2.amazonaws.com/victimscomm-prod-storage-clhgxgum05k1/uploads/2019/01/CIC-report-FINAL.pdf https://s3-eu-west-2.amazonaws.com/victimscomm-prod-storage-clhgxgum05k1/uploads/2019/01/CIC-report-FINAL.pdf https://assets.publishing.service.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/430149/QS_lobby_pack_FINAL_NEW_2.pdf#page=94 https://assets.publishing.service.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/430149/QS_lobby_pack_FINAL_NEW_2.pdf#page=94 Societies 2019, 9, 29 5 of 13 on the notion of victim-types, on victims of interpersonal crime and on those who contribute to their own victimisation. This approach signally failed to explain or advance an understanding of why and how some persons who sustain harm are regarded as victims of that harm, and others are not [31]. By contrast, it is now widely accepted that whether a person who has sustained harm is called a ‘victim’ is contingent on, and performs important social functions that follow from, the observer’s view of the world in which that harm has been sustained. In common with the label ‘offenders’, ‘victims’ are not a homogeneous subset of the population possessing certain characteristics by which they can be commonly identified and set apart from non-victims but are socially constructed, and constructed for different purposes and with different consequences. In short, ‘the very concept of victimhood can be viewed as an identity or status developed through a process of publicly validated construction’ [32] (pp. 179–180), [17] (pp. 22–24). As Nils Christie and others have observed, the concept ‘victim’ is complex, fluid and systemically contested [33], [17] (pp. 25–31), [34] (pp. 47–52), [35]. From the observer's standpoint, an initial and major problem in deciding whether to label a harmed person a ‘victim’ lies in the fact that social cues and signs may be vague or ambiguous. One response to this pervasive social phenomenon has been the development of conventions that stereotype certain instances of suffering as victimising events. Paradigm instances comprise elderly victims of robberies, burglaries and assaults, and children who are sexually abused. These are Christie’s ‘ideal victims’: Persons or categories of individuals ‘who—when hit by crime—most readily are given the complete and legitimate status of being a victim’ [33] (p. 18). Some of these conventions are formalised as legal, medical or psychiatric norms; others, such as those held within family or peer groups, may be less well defined. However well formalised, though, that response may well entail some expectations that the victim holds of those conferring the label; for example, sympathy and various forms of benign intervention designed to ameliorate the harm. The key point is that to label a person a ‘victim’ has significant resource implications for both private (emotional or other support) and public (medical and welfare provision) economies, as is the case with state compensation schemes where public funds are engaged [23] (p. 62). A corollary of the expectations that victims may have of those who have accorded them victim status is that those others may also have expectations of how victims should themselves conform to the accepted indicators of that status; to be a victim is also to occupy a social role. Ideal victims of crime do not provoke or instigate the violent encounter in which they are injured. However, as in the case of claimants to CICS 2012, discussed in the following section, drawing a normative (and in that case forensic) distinction between ideal and non-ideal victims can be highly contentious. ‘When victims are not faultless [ . . . ] They become much more problematic, both as an object of public empathy but also in terms of their entitlement to formal compensation on the part of the state’ [36] (p. 115), [37] (pp. 54–59). Victims may be expected, and be permitted, to voice anger against their offender. Nonetheless, there are limits, some legal, to what the role of a crime victim properly entails. Anger mediated through the CJS is acceptable (for example, in a victim personal statement), but not through vigilantism, where victims may, through their use of disproportionate force against the offender, themselves be labelled an offender [38]. One of victimology’s major weaknesses has been its failure to reflect on the foundational nature of criminal law [23] (pp. 49–68).16 The law does not talk of ‘victims’ but of ‘offences’, many of which, but by no means all, do contemplate harm (or its potential) to the interests of an identifiable person; that is, to their bodily or sexual integrity, or to a ‘protected characteristic’ recognised in law.17 Where such 16 It may be noted that the victim surcharge, a levy payable by offenders on conviction, applies to all offences, including those that can have no direct victim. The surcharge benefits all victims indirectly via its contribution to the government’s Victim and Witness General Fund, which supports services for victims of crime. 17 The nine ‘protected characteristics’ listed in section 4 of the Equality Act 2010 consolidate the grounds of unlawful discrimination that existed in a number of earlier enactments. See Equality and Human Rights Commission, Protected characteristics; https://www.equalityhumanrights.com/en/equality-act/protected-characteristics. https://www.equalityhumanrights.com/en/equality-act/protected-characteristics Societies 2019, 9, 29 6 of 13 characteristics were once largely confined to persons performing some official function (e.g., police officers, postal workers, the clergy), the criminal sanction now extends to offences against a wide range of personal, rather than functional, protected characteristics, notably, ‘hate crimes’ [39,40]. Some of these are discrete offences,18 while others, where they are motivated by hostility or demonstrate hostility towards the victim's disability, race, religion, sexual orientation (or transgender identity, constitute aggravating features of established offences;19 but they all may justify an uplift in sentence for those convicted of such an offence.20 Many of these extensions of the criminal sanction are the product only of the past decade or so and are symptomatic of the constant expansion of the boundaries of harm [34] (pp. 30–34), see also [35] (passim). A recent political critique identified what the author sees as the unwanted social consequences in a liberal democracy of an untrammelled notion of ‘victimhood’ [41],21 implicitly asking whether there can or should there be any limits to: • the kinds of subjects (persons/animals (warm or cold blooded)22/living/inanimate,23 environmental24), or; • the harms (bodily/mental/physical/economic/aesthetic25); • that are sustained directly or indirectly (relatives/viewers of those harms26); • at the hands of other persons (or by natural events27). Some of the examples cited in the footnotes use the label ‘victim’ to categorise the deleterious effects of the exploitation of the world’s natural resources. No doubt that exploitation deserves serious attention, but the question that they prompt is whether it is helpful or appropriate to label countries or destroyed artefacts as ‘victims’. We may recognise that the parameters that influence which harmed persons will be labelled victims and thus have a legitimate call upon society’s resources are fluid and uncertain, but there may also be a need to recognise the implications of yet broader victim paradigms. Does the promiscuous use of the word both dilute its use when applied to human suffering and raise expectations about benign interventions that cannot be met? The questions implicit in the ‘victimhood’ critique are important for the following reasons: 1. that to call someone a victim is to make a statement about our moral/ethical view of the world in which the harm was sustained; 2. that we would not normally use the label where the harm is trivial or fanciful because that devalues its use where we wish to regard seriously harmed persons as victims, for example, who have been raped or otherwise subject to unwanted sexual contact or exploitation; 3. that the use of the label carries with it a bundle of expectations that to a greater or lesser degree draw upon our private and public resources; 18 Racially or religiously aggravated offences; Crime and Disorder Act 1998, sections 28–32. 19 Criminal Justice Act 2003, sections 145–146. 20 Crown Prosecution Service, Hate crime; https://www.cps.gov.uk/hate-crime. Home Office, Hate Crime, England and wales, 2017/18; Statistical Bulletin 20/18, 16 October 2018, ISBN: 978-1-78655-706-3. 21 I also googled ‘victimhood’ and ‘we’re all victims now’, which yielded dozens of hits; ‘victimhood chic’ captures the flavour of many politically driven critiques. 22 ‘Plastic-bag-swallowing-sperm-whales-are-victims-of-our-remorseless-progress’, https://www.theguardian.com/environment/ shortcuts/2018/may/23/. 23 Archaeological Victims of ISIS Rise Again, as Replicas in Rome’, https://www.nytimes.com/2016/10/07/world/europe/rome- artifact-reconstruction-isis.html. 24 The Ivory Coast and Ghana are ‘the biggest victims of deforestation’, https://www.theguardian.com/environment/2017/sep/ 13/chocolate-industry-drives-rainforest-disaster-in-ivory-coast. 25 ‘Culturally the [Elgin marbles] are presented as abduction victims, forcibly separated from the Greek homeland’, F. Rose-Greenland, ’The Parthenon Marbles as icons of nationalism in nineteenth-century Britain’ (2013), doi:10.1111/nana.12039. 26 ‘We had to stand there and watch them burn to death’; https://www.independent.co.uk/news/uk/home-news/grenfell-tower- inquiry-victims-family-evidence-rania-ibrahim-a8363311.html. 27 ‘Philippines: Dozens killed by typhoon as rescuers rush to aid of victims in north’ https://edition.cnn.com/2018/09/16/asia/ typhoon-mangkhut-ompong-philippines-intl/index.html. https://www.cps.gov.uk/hate-crime https://www.theguardian.com/environment/shortcuts/2018/may/23/ https://www.theguardian.com/environment/shortcuts/2018/may/23/ https://www.nytimes.com/2016/10/07/world/europe/rome-artifact-reconstruction-isis.html https://www.nytimes.com/2016/10/07/world/europe/rome-artifact-reconstruction-isis.html https://www.theguardian.com/environment/2017/sep/13/chocolate-industry-drives-rainforest-disaster-in-ivory-coast https://www.theguardian.com/environment/2017/sep/13/chocolate-industry-drives-rainforest-disaster-in-ivory-coast https://www.independent.co.uk/news/uk/home-news/grenfell-tower-inquiry-victims-family-evidence-rania-ibrahim-a8363311.html https://www.independent.co.uk/news/uk/home-news/grenfell-tower-inquiry-victims-family-evidence-rania-ibrahim-a8363311.html https://edition.cnn.com/2018/09/16/asia/typhoon-mangkhut-ompong-philippines-intl/index.html https://edition.cnn.com/2018/09/16/asia/typhoon-mangkhut-ompong-philippines-intl/index.html Societies 2019, 9, 29 7 of 13 4. that the greater the number of persons included in (1), the higher the level of expectations under (3), and therefore, other things being equal, the fewer the persons in (3) whose expectations will be met; 5. that the greater the number of persons included in (1), the more likely it is that our concern for one group of victims will be displaced in favour of a more clamorous or better organised group; and 6. that the greater the number of persons included in (1), the more likely it is that the significance of the word ‘victim’ will be diluted. 3. The Criminal Injuries Compensation Scheme and the Ideal Victim Much of the literature that discusses these aspects of the social construction of victims and of the implications of that construction for persons harmed by criminal offences focuses on the use of the label in victimological and broader social discourse. With the exception of the literature examining the notion of the ‘ideal’ (female) victim of rape and the consequent implications for the law of evidence and the conduct of a trial, there has been comparatively little discussion of that construction’s implications for a crime victim’s legal remedies, whether against the offender or the state.28 Given that they are generally impecunious, civil actions for damages against offenders are very rare, and even where ordered to pay compensation on conviction to their victims, the sums are usually less than what could have been ordered in civil litigation. The reason for this is that the sentencing court must, before making an order, take account of the offender’s means.29 By contrast, CICS 2012 is a compensation scheme that offers a realistic financial remedy for victims who sustain serious physical or mental injury as a result of a violent or a sexual offence. This statutory scheme was made in 1996, replacing a common law scheme that was first introduced in 1964. The 1996 Scheme, last revised in 2012, receives nearly 33,000 applications a year, of which approximately two-thirds are resolved in the victim’s favour, as either a full or a reduced award. Compensation for the victim’s injury (or death) is assessed by reference to a tariff, which applies fixed levels of awards (from £1000 to £250,000) that notionally correspond to the severity of the injury. CICS 2012 also compensates for loss of earnings assessed by reference to statutory sick pay, and for special expenses where the victim requires long-term care. The total award in any one case is capped at £500,000; around £150 million is paid out annually; see generally [42].30 The key difference between a civil action against the offender and a claim under CICS 2012 is that the scheme is publicly funded. Whereas the victim’s own ‘non-ideal’ behaviour may have some relevance in a civil action, the distinction between ideal (‘deserving’) and non-ideal (‘undeserving’) victims continues to be central to its political legitimacy. When setting its underlying policy in the first Scheme in 1964, the government considered that it would be inappropriate for those with significant criminal records, whose own conduct before, during, or after the incident led to their being injured, or 28 A person whose conviction has been quashed by the Court of Appeal as being ‘unsafe’ is, nevertheless, not necessarily an ideal victim for the purpose of state compensation, since that decision does not of itself contain any finding as to whether that person was in fact innocent of the crime. The government’s concern that public money should be sparingly used where there has been a miscarriage of justice led to further restriction in its statutory formulation. Since 2014, it has been the case that compensation may be paid only where the Secretary of State determines that the Court of Appeal quashed the conviction in circumstances where fresh evidence shows beyond reasonable doubt that the person did not commit the offence. In Hallam, and Nealon v Secretary of State for Justice [2019] UKSC 2, the Supreme Court found that ‘the words “did not commit the offence” can be read as synonymous in this context with the words “is innocent”. It also held that the imposition of the criminal standard of proof as a condition to the possible award of compensation was not incompatible with Article 6 of the European Convention on Human Rights (presumption of innocence). 29 The total number of persons ordered in the 12 months ending June 2018 in all courts to pay compensation as the principal disposal on conviction of an offence was 4,975, of which 103 were for offences of violence against the person and 13 were for sexual offences (these numbers have declined over the past 10 years (11,058, 415 and 15 in 2008); the vast majority of orders are made for offences against property; Ministry of Justice, Overview Tables (January 2019), Tables Q5.1a and Q5.3; https://www.gov.uk/government/statistics/criminal-justice-system-statistics-quarterly-june-2018?utm_source=28904e4e- dcb3-4296-a2df-6a25e72fa679&utm_medium=email&utm_campaign=govuk-notifications&utm_content=weekly. 30 See Criminal Injuries Compensation Authority: Annual Report and Accounts 2017–2018 (House of Commons Paper 1337, July 2018). https://www.gov.uk/government/statistics/criminal-justice-system-statistics-quarterly-june-2018?utm_source=28904e4e-dcb3-4296-a2df-6a25e72fa679&utm_medium=email&utm_campaign=govuk-notifications&utm_content=weekly https://www.gov.uk/government/statistics/criminal-justice-system-statistics-quarterly-june-2018?utm_source=28904e4e-dcb3-4296-a2df-6a25e72fa679&utm_medium=email&utm_campaign=govuk-notifications&utm_content=weekly Societies 2019, 9, 29 8 of 13 who were otherwise of bad character, to receive compensation from public funds. The problem with ‘victims’ who have these kinds of personal histories is that they either resemble too closely, or were once themselves, offenders. These considerations continue to inform government policy, the structure, and the implementation of CICS 2012. It follows that not all victims succeed in their claims. Around 50% of the rejected claims fail because there was no crime of violence or the injury was valued at less than the £1000 minimum. The other 50% were rejected because they were not ‘ideal’ victims. In short, to be successful in an application to the CICA, the ideal victim is a (good) citizen who reported their injury to the police as soon as was reasonably practicable, co-operated with the criminal justice agencies in bringing their offender to justice and co-operated with the CICA,31 has no unspent convictions, did not contribute to their injuries, is of good character, and if applying for loss of earnings or special expenses (or in fatal cases, dependency) has a good work record. The following section deals more closely with three of these eligibility conditions. 3.1. The Victim’s Own Delinquent Behaviour Paragraph 25 of CICS 2012 provides that: ‘An award may be withheld or reduced where the conduct of the applicant before, during or after the incident giving rise to the criminal injury makes it inappropriate to make an award or a full award.’ CICA’s online Guide to the Scheme advises that ‘before making a payment we have to consider if your behaviour before, during or after the incident caused or contributed to the incident in which you were injured.’ It continues, ‘we will consider if you were acting in an aggressive or threatening way and provoked the incident in which you were injured; you intended to provoke an assault or fight; there was a history of violence between you and the assailant; or you were injured as a result of challenging someone over a previous incident.’32 CICA has always taken a strict view of the application of paragraph 25 and its predecessors. Where the applicant challenged or voluntarily agreed to fight their assailant but emerged the loser, their claim is likely to be wholly refused, even where the applicant was seriously injured. While their assailant’s retaliation may well be the direct result of the applicant’s own aggressive conduct, it would be wrong to conclude that paragraph 25 applies only when there is a causal link between the victim’s conduct and the criminal injury. There may, as the Guide indicates, be such a link, but the Guide is only advisory; it is not the law. As paragraph 25 makes clear, what is required is a temporal link: that the victim’s conduct occurs ‘before, during or after’ the incident. What is at issue for the scheme is not, as would be the case in a civil action against the assailant, whether it is ‘just and equitable’ to apportion financial responsibility as between the taxpayer and an applicant who caused or contributed in some way to the incident, but whether the applicant is a person whose moral worth, assessed according to strictly defined criteria, is such that their ensuing injuries should be compensated from public funds. As the judge hearing a claim that raised exactly this issue observed, ‘paragraph 25 does ‘not allow any general balancing out of the nature of a claimant’s conduct against the seriousness of the injury and other consequences’.33 Instead, given that the scheme is publicly funded, the determining question is whether it would be ‘inappropriate’ to make any award. These points are well illustrated by a comparison of the ways in which a civil court and the CICA deal with claims by offenders in respect of the injuries they receive at the hands of a householder defending their property. In Revill v Newberry, the plaintiff was a young man who had been seriously injured when shot in the chest by the householder from whose allotment shed he intended to steal some equipment. Because there had been similar incidents, the householder was lying in wait inside the shed; as he heard someone trying to break in, he discharged his shotgun through a small hole in the 31 ‘We propose that eligibility to claim from the Scheme should be tightly drawn so as to restrict awards to blameless victims of crime who fully co-operate with the criminal justice process’ [16] (p. 50). 32 https://www.gov.uk/guidance/criminal-injuries-compensation-a-guide. 33 R (SB) v First-tier Tribunal [2010] UKUT 250 (AAC), [2011] AACR 11 [27]–[31]. https://www.gov.uk/guidance/criminal-injuries-compensation-a-guide Societies 2019, 9, 29 9 of 13 door, injuring the plaintiff. In the subsequent civil action, the Court of Appeal agreed with the judge’s two-thirds reduction for the young burglar’s contributory negligence.34 By comparison, on similar facts, CICA’s then appeal body found that it would be ‘inappropriate’ that someone who was injured in the course of burgling someone’s home, and who struggled to escape and was injured when detained, should receive an award from public funds, agreeing that the claim should be entirely rejected.35 As Farmer observed of the Tony Martin case, one consequence of the contested and fluid nature of the label ‘victim’ was that the burglar whom Martin had shot in the legs while he was seeking to escape reinvented himself as a ‘victim’ of Martin’s unlawful use of force, and when he sought to sue him for his injuries, in turn relabelling the householder ‘victim’ an ‘offender’ [21] (p. 59).36 3.2. The Victim’s Criminal Record The administrative body responsible for the implementation of the pre-statutory (1964) scheme would refuse or reduce an award where the applicant had convictions that it regarded as being qualitatively or quantitatively ‘serious’, whether they were, or were not, causally related to the incident in which they were injured. This interpretation, which could include a ‘spent’ conviction under the Rehabilitation of Offenders Act 1974, was at that time approved by the Court of Appeal.37 This specific possibility was omitted in the 1996 statutory scheme, which provided instead that the CICA ‘must refuse or reduce an award to reflect unspent criminal convictions’ unless there were ‘exceptional reasons not to do so’. In order to assist in answering the question whether an award was to be refused or reduced, CICA introduced a system of ‘penalty-points’. In essence, the more severe the sentence and the shorter the period of time between the date on which it was ordered, and the date on which CICA received the application, the greater the number of penalty points, and thus the greater the likelihood of the claim being refused or rejected. Conversely, the less severe the sentence and the longer the period of that time the fewer the resulting penalty points; an outcome that sought to give the applicant credit for going straight. This approach, however, did not satisfy the government’s stated objective that taxpayer ‘cash compensation should be focused on blameless victims of the most serious crimes’ [16] (p. 3). ‘The Scheme is a taxpayer-funded expression of public sympathy and it is reasonable that there should be strict criteria around who is deemed “blameless” for the purpose of determining who should receive a share of its limited funds. We consider that, in principle, awards should only be made to those who have themselves obeyed the law and not cost society money through their offending behaviour’ [16] (para 207). Accordingly, CICS 2012 introduced stricter criteria for determining when an award would be appropriate in these cases. By paragraph 26 and Annex D paragraph 3, no award will be made where an unspent conviction resulted, broadly speaking, in either a custodial sentence or a community order. Refusal of an award in these cases is mandatory. This applies to any unspent convictions the applicant has at the time of applying or that they receive before their claim is settled. The lawfulness of this exclusionary rule was challenged on a number of grounds that primarily engaged provisions of the European Convention on Human Rights (ECHR). It is a complex case whose issues cannot be detailed here [42] (pp. 129–133), but the conclusions of the High Court and of the Court of Appeal were that however those issues were answered, the rule was not unlawful: ‘There is plainly a legitimate aim in limiting eligibility for compensation to those who are morally deserving of it, namely, “blameless 34 [1996] QB 567 (CA). 35 Criminal Injuries Compensation Appeals Panel, Annual Report and Accounts for the year ended 31 March 1997 (Cm 3840, February 1998). 36 Following this case, the law governing the use of force in self-defence was amended so that in a ‘householder’ case, the degree of force used by the ‘victim’ may be regarded as having been reasonable in the circumstances as the householder believed them to be, unless it was grossly disproportionate in those circumstances; see Collins [2016] EWHC 33 (Admin), and Cheeseman [2019] EWCA Crim 149 (CA). 37 R v Criminal Injuries Compensation Board, ex parte Thompstone and Crowe [1984] 1 WLR 1234 (CA). Societies 2019, 9, 29 10 of 13 victims of crimes of violence”.’38 As a proportion of all resolved claims, the number rejected under paragraphs 22–28 is lower than was the case before the commencement of CICS 2012, but the underlying policy remains central to its purpose. 3.3. The Victim’s Bad Character A victim’s bad character is primarily evidenced by their unspent convictions, but earlier versions of CICS 2012 enabled CICA ‘to take account of ‘other evidence available’ when determining whether to reject or reduce an award. This evidence could relate to police reports but on which the CPS had decided not to prosecute,39 or to a police caution given to the applicant. This power is now set out in paragraph 27, which provides that an award may be withheld or reduced because the applicant’s ‘character’ makes it inappropriate to make an award or a full award.40 CICA’s Guide lists the kind of character evidence that can fall within this provision. It includes any association in illegal drugs or crime, tax evasion, benefit fraud, and, as previously, police cautions, but there does not have to be evidence of a crime; an applicant who has been made the subject of an Injunction to Prevent Nuisance and Annoyance in civil proceedings,41 or a football banning order made on application to a magistrates’ court,42 may be caught by this paragraph. Nor does the relevant aspect of the applicant’s character need to have any connection with the incident in which they were injured. The application by a foreign national who had lied about having leave to remain in the UK was refused on the ground of her unlawful status. The court held that the earlier scheme ‘did not place any limitations on the type of conduct which might justify the conclusion that an applicant’s character renders an award of compensation inappropriate’.43 This general point, which could in an application on facts such as those in that case engage the discrimination provisions of the ECHR, has not been tested under CICS 2012. 4. Conclusions: Non-Ideal Victims Negligent, reckless, or intentional injuries caused by an offender against another person are, aside from any criminal liability,44 theoretically remediable in an action for damages. Other injuries, such as those that are caused by road traffic accidents, industrial processes, or contaminated vaccines, may or may not be remediable in this way. The state’s response may be to place the burden of insuring against such injuries on those who engage in the relevant activity, as in the case of compulsory motor insurance, itself to directly assume the burden of providing financial support that may in part have been funded by those receiving that support, as in the case of national insurance contributions, or to create specific ex gratia taxpayer-funded compensation schemes, as in the case of vaccine damage and the variant Creutzfeldt-Jakob disease scheme. 38 R (McNiece) v (1) Criminal Injuries Compensation Authority (2) The Lord Chancellor and Secretary of State for Justice and R (1) A (2) B v (1) Criminal Injuries Compensation Authority (2) The Lord Chancellor and Secretary of State for Justice, [2017] EWHC 2 (Admin); A and B v Criminal Injuries Compensation Authority and Secretary of State for Justice [2018] EWCA Civ 1534 (CA). Unspent convictions carrying sentences not specified in paragraph 3 will result in refusal or rejection of the claim, unless there are exceptional reasons not to do so. 39 CPS has to apply its two-stage ‘full code test’, namely, there is sufficient evidence to provide a realistic prospect of conviction, and whether it is in the public interest to prosecute; https://www.cps.gov.uk/publication/code-crown-prosecutors#section4. A conviction would require proof beyond reasonable doubt; but the standard of proof in CICS 2012 is the balance of probabilities. 40 This does not apply to the separate provisions relating to unspent convictions. 41 IPNA; these replaced Anti-Social Behaviour Orders (ASBOs; Anti-Social Behaviour, Crime and Policing Act 2014, Part 1). 42 Football Spectators Act 1989 ss 14A and 14B. Under section 14B(2), it is necessary to show only that the person ‘has at any time caused or contributed to any violence or disorder in the United Kingdom or elsewhere’ but does not depend on a conviction, as does section 14A. 43 Andronati v Criminal Injuries Compensation Appeals Panel [2006] EWHC 1420 (Admin) [9]. 44 Negligence alone is generally insufficient for an offence against the person, but gross negligence may be sufficient basis for a conviction of manslaughter where the victim dies. https://www.cps.gov.uk/publication/code-crown-prosecutors#section4 Societies 2019, 9, 29 11 of 13 These instances by no means fully recognise these many alternative compensation systems,45 of which CICS 2012 is one such alternative. It does not substitute for a known offender against whom a remedy is possible, either via a civil action, or a compensation order on conviction. In both cases, any sums recovered are fully deductible from any CICA award; there is no double recovery at the taxpayer’s expense. However, as such sums are likely to fall short of what could be recovered from an insured defendant, or one with sufficient means, CICS 2012 stands as an additional source of compensation, and where, as is frequently the case, the offender is unknown or not brought to trial, it is the only source; a remedy of last resort. All taxpayer-funded schemes whose purpose is, as in the case of the instances above, to provide financial redress for injuries that public policy dictates should not fall unmitigated upon the individual, by definition specify those eligibility criteria with which the injured person must comply. These criteria may be characterised as a ‘payment trigger’ whose primary function is ‘to select worthy claimants from the less deserving and to make payments only to the former’ [44] (p. 640). In the case of CICS 2012, this measure of desert is implicitly achieved by drawing a line between ideal and non-ideal victims of violent and sexual crime, and explicitly so in the case of the various disentitling provisions discussed above. Unless they are applicants whose claims have been refused or any award reduced, there is probably very little wider societal awareness of the state’s restrictions on non-ideal victims’ access to this particular source of public funds. The point being made in this article is that CICS 2012 is an exemplar of the legal implications of an unsympathetic construction of an applicant’s possible social status as a victim of a violent or sexual crime. This construction in turn illustrates one consequence of the contested cultural representations that continue to shape perceptions of victims of crime [45]. It also, secondly, illustrates the inevitable legal difficulties that attend political and criminal justice discourse and practice, which are, similarly, a consequence of that contest. Funding: This research received no external funding. Conflicts of Interest: The authors declare no conflict of interest. References 1. Rock, P. On Becoming a Victim. In New Visions of Crime Victims; Hoyle, C., Wilson, R., Eds.; Hart Publishing: Oxford, UK, 2002; pp. 1–22, ISBN 1-84113-280-2. 2. Walklate, S.; Mawby, R. Critical Victimology; Sage Publications: London, UK, 1994; pp. 69–94, ISBN 0-8039-8512-6. 3. Doak, J. Victims’ Rights, Human Rights and Criminal Justice; Hart Publishing: Oxford, UK, 2008; ISBN 978-1-84113-603-5. 4. Kearon, T.; Godfrey, B. Setting the Scene: A Question of History. In Handbook of Victims and Victimology; Walklate, S., Ed.; Willan Publishing: Devon, UK, 2007; ISBN 978-1-84392-257-5. 5. Sebba, L. Third Parties: Victims and the Criminal Justice System; Ohio State University Press: Columbus, OH, USA, 1996; ISBN 0-8142-0664-6. 6. Shapland, J.; Hall, M. Victims at Court: Necessary Accessories or Principal Players at Centre Stage. In Hearing the Victim; Bottoms, A., Roberts, J., Eds.; Willan Publishing: Devon, UK, 2010; pp. 163–198, ISBN 978-1-84392-272-8. 7. Kirchengast, T. The Victim in Criminal Law and Justice; Palgrave Macmillan: New York, NY, USA, 2006; ISBN 978-1-4039-86 10-8. 8. Radzinowicz, L. A History of English Criminal Law; Stevens and Sons: London, UK, 1956; Volume 2. 9. Armstrong, A.; McAra, L. Audiences, Borders, Architecture: The Contours of Control. In Perspectives on Punishment; Armstrong, A., McAra, L., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2006; ISBN 0-19-927877-6. 45 See [43], (pp. 99–121), [43]. Societies 2019, 9, 29 12 of 13 10. Home Office. Rebalancing the Criminal Justice System in Favour of the Law-Abiding Majority; Produced by COI on behalf of the Home Office, July 2006. Ref: 275921; Home Office: London, UK, 2006. 11. O’Mahoney, D.; Doak, J. Reimagining Restorative Justice; Hart Publishing: Oxford, UK, 2017; ISBN 978-1-84946-056-9. 12. Sanders, A. Victim Participation in an Exclusionary Criminal Justice System. In New Visions of Crime Victims; Hoyle, C., Wilson, R., Eds.; Hart Publishing: Oxford, UK, 2002; pp. 197–222, ISBN 1-84113-280-2. 13. Attorney General’s Office. Rebuilding Lives: Supporting Victims of Crime; Cm 6705; The Stationery Office: London, UK, 2005; ISBN 0101670524. 14. Tonry, M. Rebalancing the Criminal Justice System in Favour of the Victim: The Costly Consequences of Populist Rhetoric. In Hearing the Victim; Bottoms, A., Roberts, J., Eds.; Willan Publishing: Devon, UK, 2010; pp. 72–103, ISBN 978-1-84392-272-8. 15. McEwan, J. From Adversarialism to Managerialism: Criminal Justice in Transition. Leg. Stud. 2011, 31, 519–546. [CrossRef] 16. Ministry of Justice. Getting it Right for Victims and Witnesses; Cm 8288; The Stationery Office: London, UK, 2012; ISBN 9780101828826. 17. Spalek, B. Crime Victims: Theory, Policy and Practice; Palgrave Macmillan: Basingstoke, UK, 2006; ISBN-10: 1-4039-3542-4. 18. Ministry of Justice. Code of Practice for Victims of Crime; updated to October 2018; The Stationery Office: London, UK, 2015; ISBN 9781474125390. 19. Matravers, M. The Victim, the State, and Civil Society. In Hearing the Victim; Bottoms, A., Roberts, J., Eds.; Willan Publishing: Devon, UK, 2010; pp. 1–16, ISBN 978-1-84392-272-8. 20. Loader, I. In Search of Civic Policing: Recasting The ‘Peelian’ Principles. Crim. Law Philos. 2016, 10, 427–440. [CrossRef] 21. Dean, H. Welfare Rights and Social Policy; Routledge: Abingdon, UK, 2002; ISBN 978-1-317904-731. 22. Dwyer, P. Welfare Rights And Responsibilities: Contesting Social Citizenship; The Policy Press: Bristol, UK, 2000; ISBN 978-1-86134-204-1. 23. Farmer, L. Tony Martin and the Nightbreakers: Criminal Law, Victims, and the Power to Punish. In Perspectives on Punishment; Armstrong, S., McAra, L., Eds.; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2006; ISBN 0-19-927877-6. 24. Miers, D. The Responsibilities and the Rights of Victims of Crime. Mod. Law Rev. 1992, 55, 482–505. [CrossRef] 25. Hall, M. Victims of Crime: Policy and Practice in Criminal Justice; Willan Publishing: Devon, UK, 2009; ISBN 978-1-84392-381-7. 26. Hoyano, L. Cross-Examination of Sexual Assault Complainants on Previous Sexual Behaviour: Views from the Barristers’ Row. Crim. Law Rev. 2019, 77–114. 27. Attorney General’s Office. Review of the Efficiency and Effectiveness of Disclosure in the Criminal Justice System; Cm 9735; The Stationary Office: London, UK, 2018; ISBN 978-1-5286-0873-2. 28. Roberts, J.; Erez, E. Communication at sentencing: The expressive function of Victim Impact Statements. In Hearing the Victim; Bottoms, A., Roberts, J., Eds.; Willan Publishing: Devon, UK, 2010; pp. 232–249, ISBN 978-1-84392-272-8. 29. HM Government. Victims Strategy; Cm 9700; The Stationery Office: London, UK, 2018; ISBN 978-1-5286-0780-3. 30. Condry, R. The Parent as Paradoxical Victim. In Reconceptualizing Critical Victimology; Spencer, D., Walklate, S., Eds.; Lexington Books: Lanham, MD, USA, 2016; pp. 45–61, ISBN 978149851064. 31. Miers, D. Positivist Victimology: A Critique. Int. Rev. Vict. 1989, 1, 219–230. [CrossRef] 32. Winter, J. Notions of Victimhood in the Trial of Rose West. In New Visions of Crime Victims; Hoyle, C., Wilson, R., Eds.; Hart Publishing: Oxford, UK, 2002; pp. 173–196, ISBN 1-84113-280-2. 33. Christie, N. The Ideal Victim. In From Crime Policy to Victim Policy; Fattah, E., Ed.; Palgrave Macmillan: London, UK, 1986; pp. 17–30, ISBN 0-333-39994-3. 34. Hall, M. Victims and Policy Making: A Comparative Perspective; Willan Publishing: Devon, UK, 2010; ISBN 978-1-84392-381-7. 35. Duggan, M. (Ed.) Revisiting the ‘Ideal Victim’; Policy Press: Bristol, UK, 2018; ISBN 978-1-4473-3876-5. 36. McEvoy, K.; McConnachie, K. Victimhood and Transitional Justice. In Reconceptualizing Critical Victimology; Spencer, D., Walklate, S., Eds.; Lexington Books: Lanham, MD, USA, 2016; pp. 111–132, ISBN 978149851064. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1748-121X.2011.00201.x http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11572-014-9318-1 http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-2230.1992.tb00927.x http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/026975809000100301 Societies 2019, 9, 29 13 of 13 37. Hamill, H. Victims of Paramilitary Punishment Beatings in Belfast. In New Visions of Crime Victims; Hoyle, C., Wilson, R., Eds.; Hart Publishing: Oxford, UK, 2002; pp. 49–69, ISBN 1-84113-280-2. 38. Miers, D. Taking the Law into Their Own Hands: Victims as Offenders. In Integrating a Victim Perspective within Criminal Justice; Crawford, A., Goodey, J., Eds.; Ashgate: Dartmouth, NH, USA, 2000; pp. 77–96, ISBN 1-84014-486-6. 39. Chakraborti, N. Victims of Hate. In Reconceptualizing Critical Victimology; Spencer, D., Walklate, S., Eds.; Lexington Books: Lanham, MD, USA, 2016; pp. 63–77, ISBN 978149851064. 40. Mason-Bish, H. Creating ideal victims in hate crime policy. In Revisiting the ‘Ideal Victim’; Duggan, M., Ed.; Policy Press: Bristol, UK, 2018; pp. 43–61, ISBN 978-1-4473-3876-5. 41. Green, D. We’re (Nearly) All Victims Now! How Political Correctness Is Undermining Our Liberal Culture; Civitas, Institute for the Study of Civil Society: London, UK, 2006; ISBN 9781903386538. 42. Miers, D. Criminal Injuries Compensation: State and Offender Compensation for Violent Crime; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2018; ISBN 978-0-19-880662-2. 43. Deakin, S.; Johnston, A.; Markesinis, B. Markesinis and Deakin’s Tort Law; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 2013; ISBN 978-0-959198-5. 44. Macleod, S.; Hodges, C. Redress Schemes for Personal Injuries; Hart Publishing: Oxford, UK, 2017; ISBN 9781509916610. 45. Walklate, S. Victims: Needs Rights and Justice. In Routledge International Handbook of Criminology and Human Rights; Weber, L., Fishwick, E., Marmo, M., Eds.; Routledge: New York, NY, USA, 2017; pp. 71–79, ISBN 1-138-93117-6. © 2019 by the author. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/). http://creativecommons.org/ http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/. Victims and the Criminal Justice System The Social Construction of Victims of Crime The Criminal Injuries Compensation Scheme and the Ideal Victim The Victim’s Own Delinquent Behaviour The Victim’s Criminal Record The Victim’s Bad Character Conclusions: Non-Ideal Victims References work_4rpgbq7jvve4nguwoisfwjtknm ---- 3. Posada y González REV I S TA D E ECO N O M Í A I N S T I T U C I O NA L , Nº 2, PRI M ER SEM ES T R E/2000 EL GASTO EN DEFENSA, JUSTICIA Y SEGURIDAD* Carlos Esteban Posada P.** Francisco González*** 1. INTRODUCCIÓN E s común afirmar que Colombia sobresale en el campointernacional por sus altas tasas de delincuencia, esto es, por el número de asesinatos, secuestros, hurtos, actos de terrorismo, etc., con respecto al tamaño de la población1. En realidad esta tasa no sólo fue bastante alta en los años 70 sino que ascendió rápidamente en la primera mitad de los años 80 (gráfico 1.1). Los delitos contra la vida (homicidios intencionales, etc.) y la libertad individual (secuestros, etc.), cuyas tasas no fueron espe- cialmente altas en los años sesenta y setenta, empezaron a crecer rápidamente desde mediados o fines de los años setenta. En 1991 la tasa de homicidios llegó a su nivel máximo: 92.6 personas por cada 100.000 habitantes (gráfico 1.2); de éstos sólo 14% corresponden a accidentes de tránsito. Posteriormente esta tasa ha declinado muy lentamente. * Las opiniones contenidas en este documento sólo comprometen a sus autores y no al Banco de la República ni a su Junta Directiva, ni al Departamento Nacional de Planeación, ni a la Universidad Externado de Colombia. Una versión anterior recibió valiosos comentarios de Luis Eduardo Arango, Daniel Mejía, Adriana Pontón, Oscar Martínez y (General) Gabriel Pontón. Los autores agra- decen al Banco de la República, al DNP y a la Universidad Externado de Colombia su apoyo para la realización de este trabajo. ** Investigador de la Subgerencia de Estudios Económicos del Banco de la República. *** Jefe de la División de Proyecciones y Mediciones de la Unidad de Análisis Macroeconómico del Departamento Nacional de Planeación y Profesor de la Facultad de Economía de la Universidad Externado de Colombia. 1. Además de los delitos contra la vida e integridad personal y contra el patri- monio se encuentran otros delitos oficialmente c lasificados así: “libertad y pudor sexual”, “libertad individual” (secuestro, etc.), “administración pública”, “admi- nistración de justicia”, “seguridad pública”, “el orden económico y social”, “la fe pública” y “otros títulos”. Carlos Esteban Posada - Francisco González54 En delitos de homicidio Colombia tiene un desempeño sobresaliente. Así, en una muestra de 48 países desarrollados y en desarrollo no africanos Colombia figuró como el país con la máxima tasa de homicidios intencionales, 77.5 anuales por cada 100.000 habitantes, en promedio, durante el cuatrienio 1986-89, seguido por Brasil, con una tasa de 24.6 homicidios anuales por 100.000 habitantes en un período casi igual2-3. Gráfico 1.1: Gráfico 1.2: 2. Gaitán (1995); véase también Montenegro y Posada (1995) y Montenegro et al. (2000). Las cifras sobre delitos se encuentran en DANE (1995) y DANE y Ministerio de Justicia (1996), así como las cifras de homicidios según Policía Nacional; las cifras de homicidios cuya fuente original es el Instituto de Medicina Legal fueron obtenidas de una base de datos del DNP. 3. Pero en años recientes algunos países centroamericanos han registrado tasas de homicidios intencionales mayores. Por ejemplo, El Salvador tiene una de 120 EL G A S T O EN D EF EN S A , J U S T I C I A Y S E G U R I DA D 55 Casi simultáneamente con el aumento del crimen en general y de los asesinatos y secuestros (tanto los de origen común como los ejer- cidos por las organizaciones guerrilleras y paramilitares) la proporción entre el gasto público en defensa, justicia y seguridad (DJS) y el producto interno bruto creció, y lo hizo hasta 1997 (gráfico 1.3)4. Aunque es natural pensar que el aumento de tal gasto ha sido una respuesta de la sociedad ante el avance de la criminalidad, caben dos preguntas al respecto. La primera se refiere a la racionalidad del aumento del gasto DJS, en vista de que éste tiene, como todo gasto, un costo de oportunidad. En términos más concretos lo que se quiere decir es que no es obvio que todo aumento de la criminalidad induzca un incremento en el nivel óptimo de gasto DJS, y en cualquier magnitud, así que valdría la pena establecer las condiciones bajo las cuales son óptimos ciertos niveles y aumentos del gasto. Gráfico 1.3: La otra pregunta es esta: ¿cuáles son las condiciones de existencia de una sustitución o, por el contrario, una complementariedad en el margen entre las variaciones del gasto óptimo y los cambios en su grado de eficiencia? En lo que sigue se intentará responder las preguntas anteriores de una forma abstracta y simplificada. La última sección contiene un resumen sin detalles formales y unas conclusiones. En vista de que homicidios por 100.000 habitantes (Business Week, L. A. edition, mayo 8/2000, p. 4). 4. Las cifras de gasto son de ejecución presupuestal (diferentes a las de caja) e incluyen gastos en cabeza del Ministerio de Justicia, Fiscalía, Rama Judicial, Policía, Defensa Nacional; fuente: Contraloría Gener al de la Repúblic a (información tomada de base de datos del Banco de la Repúblic a). Carlos Esteban Posada - Francisco González56 las secciones analíticas utilizan algunas expresiones matemáticas hemos tratado que el lector puede recibir los mensajes centrales de este documento aun si sólo lee esta introducción, las secciones penúltima (“Datos e interpretaciones”) y última (“Resumen y conclu- siones”), y observa los gráficos. Antes de terminar esta introducción son necesarias dos aclara- ciones adicionales. En las secciones teóricas nos ocuparemos de dos de los principales componentes de la criminalidad: la pérdida de riqueza que sufren los ofendidos (asociada a diferentes modalidades de fraude, hurto, atraco, extorsión y secuestro, etc.) y los homicidios intencionales (diferentes a los derivados de accidentes de tránsito). El modelo hace abstracción de otro tipo de delitos. En general, la violencia política y la criminalidad son dos cosas distintas. La primera siempre es colectiva, ataca un orden social y sus promotores pretenden ofrecer, a la postre, un bien público; la segunda se puede definir por la carencia de los atributos anteriores5. Con todo, en Colombia, y al menos desde principios de los años 80, la línea divisoria es bastante tenue y fluctuante (dado el modus operandi de nuestros subversivos), y, además, las acciones guerrilleras han contribuido a congestionar la labor de la policía y la justicia y a generar, entonces, “externalidades positivas” a la industria del delito común6. Por tanto, en este trabajo no se consideró pertinente realizar la separación de conceptos y estadísticas entre delitos “políticos” y “comunes”, y, en consecuencia, utilizamos un modelo en el cual los gastos en defensa, justicia y seguridad se agrupan en uno solo ya que los objetivos de tal gasto, aunque distintos en principio, convergen en la práctica colombiana un uno solo: tratar de proteger a la sociedad civil de los atentados contra la vida, la libertad individual y el patrimonio. Esto significa que estamos considerando el gasto en defensa externa y el peligro de agresión por otros países como elementos constantes y, por ende, carentes de importancia para el análisis en el margen. 2. EL PROBLEMA DEL AGENTE REPRESENTATIVO Y LAS PÉRDIDAS MATERIALES De acuerdo con los propósitos enunciados previamente lo que se expondrá a continuación no es un modelo de crimen sino un modelo 5. Gupta (1990; pp. 4-5). 6. Una descripción de esto se encuentra en Rubio (1999), Gaviria (2000) y Montenegro et al. (2000). EL G A S T O EN D EF EN S A , J U S T I C I A Y S E G U R I DA D 57 de las consecuencias del crimen sobre el gasto óptimo en DJS. El modelo es una adaptación de uno bastante conocido y utilizado por los economistas: el modelo de un agente racional (optimizador), representativo de la “sociedad civil” o de los constituyentes primarios7. Como es lo usual, se supone que este agente tiene un horizonte infinito de planeación (o, de manera equivalente, se preocupa por el futuro de sus hijos, y éstos de sus hijos, y así sucesivamente). En el caso específico de las consecuencias del crimen, supondremos que el agente representativo no pierde capacidad de razonamiento ni de decisión por las acciones criminales ni toma en cuenta las preferencias u objetivos del criminal; simplemente percibe de manera lúcida el efecto de las acciones criminales, así que no es un modelo de interacciones estratégicas. En una sección posterior se justificará este supuesto. El agente representativo logra hacer previsiones acertadas, así que las pérdidas por acciones criminales no llegan a extremos de inducir la irracionalidad en los procesos de formación de expectativas o de capital, ni crear comportamientos explosivos de la productividad marginal del capital u otras variables pertinentes8. El modelo es de economía cerrada y supone que se produce un solo bien que puede ser utilizado para el consumo corriente, para la protección o para la inversión. La parte del bien no consumida ni utilizada para protección, es decir, el ahorro, se destina a acrecentar la capacidad productiva. La riqueza material de la sociedad es, para simplificar las cosas, su capital productivo y supondremos, también para simplificar, que no se desgasta por su uso normal ni se hace obsoleto por el cambio técnico; sólo sufre deterioro por acciones criminales. Se puede considerar, entonces, que el gasto DJS reduce la pérdida asociada a los fenómenos de criminalidad. Lo afirmado en el último párrafo, relativo a las consecuencias de las acciones criminales y al efecto reparador (y preventivo) del gasto DJS, se expresa formalmente así: 7. Para nuestros propósitos debemos excluir de los conceptos de “sociedad civil” o de “constituyentes primarios” a los delincuentes. 8. Esto supone, además, que: a) los criminales (efectivos y potenciales) no tienen capacidad de influir de manera decisiva sobre el gasto público en defensa, justicia y seguridad, o b) que la riqueza apropiada por los criminales no llegará, en ningún caso, a ser de un nivel tan grande que lleve a que éstos puedan influir en las decisiones sobre tal gasto. Carlos Esteban Posada - Francisco González58 Por ende: Siendo: k t : capital (su valor real) al comienzo del período “t”; I t : inversión bruta en capital o inversión antes de descontar las pérdidas por destrucción criminal; δ t : valor real destruido por unidad de capital; δ 0 : valor real que se destruiría en ausencia del gasto DJS (o componente autónomo o exógeno de la destrucción criminal); S t : gasto DJS real; γ : índice de eficiencia del gasto DJS por unidad de capital; γ 0 : componente autónomo del índice de eficiencia; γ 1 δ 0 : componente del índice de eficiencia inducido por la destrucción criminal. Este componente podrá ser positivo (cuando la criminalidad produce una reacción que eleva la eficiencia: γ 1 > 0) o negativo (caso en el cual la destrucción criminal tiende a generar menor eficiencia del gasto DJS: γ 1 < 0). Más adelante veremos cuál es la consecuencia de hacer una conjetura razonable: que la destrucción criminal induce menor eficiencia (γ 1 < 0). Así, la formulación de la destrucción total, δ t k t , y de la eficiencia total del gasto DJS, γ, reconoce que esta última puede depender parcialmente de la violencia: a mayor criminalidad mayor sería la depreciación bruta, δ 0 , o depreciación sin incluir el efecto disuasivo, preventivo y reparador del gasto DJS; y de la destrucción criminal podría incidir parcialmente y de manera positiva o negativa en la eficiencia del gasto DJS. Además, la utilidad del agente representativo depende del consumo y de la tranquilidad que le reporta un cierto gasto en seguridad y justicia. El problema del agente representativo es hacer máximo el valor presente de la serie de sus utilidades periódicas (U): EL G A S T O EN D EF EN S A , J U S T I C I A Y S E G U R I DA D 59 Sujeto a: Siendo β el factor de descuento e idéntico al inverso de 1 más la tasa de descuento (ρ) de la utilidad futura: β≡1/(1+ρ); u es la utilidad periódica percibida por el agente, que depende positivamente de dos variables: consumo corriente (c) y gasto real DJS (S), así que se supone, por simplicidad, que el nivel real de gasto DJS es, en sí mismo, un indicador de la fuente de utilidad reportada por la tranquilidad que induce, dados unos parámetros de eficiencia (γ 0 , γ 1 ) conocidos por el agente9: σ y ε son dos parámetros, cada uno de ellos igual al inverso de la elasticidad de la utilidad marginal con respecto a cada variable, y χ puede entenderse como un índice de preferencia o importancia relativa asignada a la seguridad en la función de utilidad. De otra parte, se supone que el producto (y) depende del capital, dados un factor de productividad (A) y una elasticidad del producto con respecto al capital (α), y que los gastos DJS se financian plenamente con impuestos de suma fija (T). Además, supondremos que se cumple la llamada “condición de transversalidad”, a saber: el valor presente de los gastos del agente representativo es igual al valor presente de sus ingresos netos de impuestos10. Por tanto, el problema es maximizar el valor presente de las serie de utilidades periódicas: 9. En Sandler y Hartley (1995) o en Davoodi et al. (1999) se encuentran ejemplos de funciones de utilidad con argumentos similares. 10. Como se obser va, la función de utilidad es aditiva y separable en sus dos argumentos y cada utilidad periódica es independiente de las anter iores y posteriores y es aditiva intertemporalmente; estos supuestos se hacen por facilidad analítica pero tienen implicaciones que consideraremos de poca importancia en Carlos Esteban Posada - Francisco González60 Max. U = (1) Las condiciones necesarias de óptimo (“condiciones de primer orden”) son las siguientes11: (2) (3) La ecuación 2 y la condición de transversalidad permiten utilizar la siguiente hipótesis: (4) Siendo W t el valor presente esperado de la riqueza (o valor estimado en “t” de la serie de ingresos netos futuros) y l la “propensión” a consumir la riqueza12. Así, el reemplazo de 4 en 3 permite deducir el gasto DJS óptimo presente: (3a) Dados los parámetros asociados a las preferencias χ, ∈ , δ, y λ, se predice que a mayor riqueza o a mayor eficiencia autónoma del gasto este caso. Además, la función de utilidad periódica debería escribirse, en rigor así: Pero para simplificar la notación aquí se sigue la práctica generalizada de omitir –1 en los numeradores. 11. Condiciones de máximo derivando con respecto a k s (para s > t) y a S s . 12. Una justificación y descripción en términos específicos de esta hipótesis se encuentra en Blanchard y Fischer (1989, cap. 2 y 3). EL G A S T O EN D EF EN S A , J U S T I C I A Y S E G U R I DA D 61 en seguridad (γ 0 ) mayor será el nivel óptimo del gasto DJS13. Además, si el parámetro γ 1 es positivo, es decir, si la destrucción criminal genera más eficiencia en el gasto DJS, entonces se predice que a mayor destrucción criminal mayor será el nivel óptimo de este gasto. De manera simétrica, si el parámetro γ 1 es negativo, caso que parece más factible en la realidad y bajo el cual la destrucción criminal genera menor eficiencia del gasto en seguridad14, entonces a mayor destrucción criminal menor será el gasto óptimo15. Finalmente: (5) Según esta última expresión, la relación entre el gasto óptimo DJS y el consumo crecerá pari passu con la riqueza esperada si σ /ε es mayor que 1, y viceversa en el caso contrario. De manera intuitiva la ecuación 5 nos dice, entre otras cosas, lo siguiente: dados los indicadores de eficiencia (γ 0 y γ 1 ) y destrucción autónoma (δ 0 ), el incremento en la riqueza esperada conducirá a elevar la relación entre el gasto óptimo DJS y el consumo si la sociedad le asigna un peso relativamente mayor a la seguridad que al consumo (esto es, si σ > ∈ ) cuando pondera, en el margen, sus fuentes de uti- lidad; de lo contrario, los aumentos de la riqueza mantendrán constante o harán decrecer la relación entre el gasto DJS y el consumo. De una manera natural surge una pregunta básica: ¿qué efectos tiene un aumento del grado autónomo de destrucción criminal, δ 0 ? La respuesta no es sencilla. En primer lugar, si se juzga transitorio este aumento no deberíamos esperar una reducción de la riqueza; en tal caso, el efecto de un aumento de δ 0 sería elevar el gasto en seguridad sólo si el parámetro γ 1 es positivo. En segundo lugar, si el aumento del grado de destrucción se juzga permanente deberíamos esperar una reducción de la riqueza; pero una caída de la riqueza conducirá a elevar la relación entre el gasto DJS y el consumo sólo si σ / ∈ es 13. Con su modelo de criminalidad Ehrlich (1973) genera también un nivel óptimo de gasto en protección que tiene esta implicación. Mejía (2000, con base en Lapan y Sandler 1988) también hace explícita esta implic ación en un modelo de secuestros. 14. En Posada (1994) y Gavir ia (2000) se encuentran justificaciones e ilustraciones de esta hipótesis; Fajnzylber et al. (1998) la aplican a su trabajo empírico. 15. Pero en el modelo de Ehrlich (1973) la tasa de criminalidad siempre tiene un efecto positivo sobre el gasto óptimo en DJS. Carlos Esteban Posada - Francisco González62 mayor que 1 y si γ 1 ≥ 0; de lo contrario (es decir, cuando σ / ∈ es mayor que 1 y cuando γ 1 < 0) el aumento de la intensidad de la destrucción criminal conducirá a reducir el gasto DJS16. Supongamos que σ ≥ ∈ , y que la criminalidad tiene un efecto negativo sobre la eficiencia del gasto DJS: γ 1 < 0. En tal caso un incremento del grado de destrucción ha de conducir a una disminución del gasto DJS; esto, a su vez, conducirá a la reducción de la riqueza de la sociedad. Si ante una creciente oleada de destrucción criminal la sociedad no responde elevando la eficiencia autónoma de su gasto en defensa (elevando γ 0 ) entonces se puede caer en una trampa: a mayor destrucción de capital, menor riqueza esperada, menor eficiencia del gasto DJS y menor nivel del mismo; esto podría, incluso, aunque no está contemplado por el modelo, conducir a nuevos ataques. 3. EL RIESGO DE MUERTE Y LOS HOMICIDIOS La actividad criminal incluye la eliminación de vidas humanas. Reconocer este hecho implica, para los propósitos actuales, revisar el modelo anterior. El primer paso para enfrentar el tema de las consecuencias de los homicidios es adicionar algunos supuestos para incluir este asunto. Si suponemos, para evitar complicaciones innecesarias, que: a) el núcleo básico de la sociedad civil es una familia compuesta por el padre, la madre, una hija y un hijo (un caso de reproducción demo- gráfica simple17), b) que la pareja padre-madre, denominada en lo sucesivo “el agente representativo”, toma decisiones de consumo, gasto DJS y ahorro pensando en sí misma y en sus hijos, y que éstos lo harán así cuando se casen y tengan hijos, y así sucesivamente, y c) que los homicidas no ponen en peligro la estructura ni la reproducción demográfica supuestas, puesto que sólo pueden, con su acto criminal, anticipar el momento de la muerte del padre o de la madre pero no hasta el punto de impedir que previamente hayan procreado, entonces se puede considerar que el modelo anterior, con ligeras modificaciones, puede seguir siendo útil para el análisis18. 16. Esta discusión podría ser más precisa y formal si se considerase alguna ley de evolución en el tiempo de d 0 , como, por ejemplo, suponer que es variable en el tiempo (δ 0t ) y que, o bien sigue un proceso estacionario (en media y varianza), de manera que cualquier choque soportado por d 0 sólo tiene efectos transitorios, o bien suponer que sigue un “paseo aleatorio” de manera que los choques tienen efectos permanentes. Con todo, creemos que los aspectos básicos de la discusión (y en vista de que no haremos estimaciones econométricas) se puede entender bajo la forma actualmente utilizada en el texto principal. 17. Desde David Ricardo ha sido usual tal supuesto par a entender las propiedades de un equilibrio general en estado estacionario. EL G A S T O EN D EF EN S A , J U S T I C I A Y S E G U R I DA D 63 El segundo paso es reflexionar sobre el sentido de la ecuación 4. Según esta, el consumo presente depende del valor esperado actual de la riqueza, dada una “propensión a consumir” la riqueza que se denominó λ. Supondremos ahora que el factor λ depende negativa- mente del factor de descuento β19. Es decir, entre más impaciente es el agente (o entre mayor sea la tasa de descuento, o menor β, que aplica a la utilidad futura), mayor es, ceteris paribus, su consumo presente con respecto a su riqueza. Como resultado de lo anterior, se puede suponer que el factor de descuento del agente representativo de vida finita (el agente “υ”) es βυ, menor que el factor β correspondiente al caso del agente repre- sentativo de vida infinita de las secciones previas: En otros términos, la conciencia de la mortalidad (o de la posibilidad de una muerte prematura) genera mayor impaciencia: un descuento mayor de la utilidad futura20. Además, el supuesto de similitud de los agentes en todo lo demás, salvo en su percepción de un mayor o menor riesgo de muerte, permite considerar que el factor agregado de descuento, que llamaremos βa, es un promedio de los factores individuales de descuento, ponderado por la participación de cada agente en la población total21, así que: Dado lo anterior, podemos suponer que el consumo agregado (ca) es el producto de una propensión agregada a consumir la riqueza (λa, υ 18. Nuestra inspiración y referencia básica en lo que sigue es el modelo de Blanchard (1985), que generaliza el modelo del agente representativo de horizonte infinito al caso de vidas finitas; véase también su exposición en Blanchard y Fischer (1989, cap. 3, pp. 115 y ss). La consecuencia práctica de incluir el caso de vidas finitas es modificar y reinterpretar (desde el punto de vista económico) algunos parámetros del modelo de vida infinita; por tanto, se puede mantener la metáfora del horizonte de planeación infinito para la sociedad en su conjunto, sin que formalmente se alteren las condiciones de óptimo ni las de equilibrio de los mercados (Cfr., ibidem). 19. Obstfeld y Rogoff, 1996, cap. 2, pp. 70 y ss, y Blanchard y Fischer, 1989, cap. 3, pp. 119 y ss. 20. Blanchard y Fischer (obra y partes citadas). 21. Alternativamente, podríamos suponer (para evitar complicaciones asociadas a la agregación) que la población incluida en la sociedad civil se compone sólo de la pareja padre-madre y de sus dos hijos, así que sólo habría un agente representativo. Carlos Esteban Posada - Francisco González64 ella misma un promedio ponderado de las propensiones individuales) por el nivel esperado de la riqueza agregada (Wa): Y como habíamos supuesto que la propensión a consumir la riqueza depende inversamente del factor de descuento, entonces la propensión media a consumir la riqueza en una sociedad de mortales (λa) es mayor que la del modelo anterior: De otra parte, parece natural considerar que el parámetro χ, que relaciona de manera positiva el gasto DJS con la utilidad que éste reporta al agente, y el parámetro 1 / ∈ , o elasticidad de la utilidad marginal con respecto al gasto DJS, son mayores en el caso de vidas finitas y sujetas al riesgo de muerte por homicidio que en el de vida infinita. Puesto que la función de utilidad de cada agente debe tener un parámetro similar, entonces: Tales condiciones implican, entre otras cosas, que los parámetros individuales son iguales a los del análisis agregado. Finalmente debe- mos reconsiderar el asunto de la pérdida social asociada a los homi- cidios y su relación con el gasto DJS. La manera más económica de abordar este asunto es suponer que la riqueza social o capital productivo agregado es una combinación de capital material y capital humano22, y que el producto no destinado al consumo ni a la protección se destina a la acumulación de capital físico y humano. Dados sus precios relativos las proporciones de la mezcla de capital físico y humano serán constantes, así que podremos hablar de una magnitud llamada capital o riqueza total agregada, Wa. Podemos suponer que los precios relativos de ambas clases de capital son constantes o, de manera más amplia, que sus eventuales variaciones no tienen efectos que vayan en contravía de las conclusiones derivadas de este análisis. 22. Por ejemplo, una función CES o Cobb-Douglas de ambos elementos. Este es un recurso usual en la literatura moderna de crecimiento económico. EL G A S T O EN D EF EN S A , J U S T I C I A Y S E G U R I DA D 65 El caso de vidas finitas (o, si se quiere, de posible muerte prematura) permite, entonces, considerar que la criminalidad se expresa como una destrucción (parcial) no sólo de capital material sino también de capital humano. La destrucción de capital, δka, en el nivel agregado, será formalmente similar a la definida anteriormente: Pero ahora nos referimos a destrucción de capital agregado (físico y humano), en términos de intensidad de actos delincuenciales que eliminan personas además de capital físico, y a una cierta capacidad del gasto DJS, que llamamos γS, para contrarrestar, impedir y disuadir ambas clases de delitos y compensar sus efectos. Teniendo en cuenta lo anterior, se debe reescribir la condición que establece la relación óptima entre los niveles agregados del gastos DJS (S t a) y el consumo así: (5a) Las consideraciones anteriores permiten suponer, como ya se dijo, que la existencia de homicidios, si es un hecho que se juzga permanente, implicará parámetros χa, λa de magnitud mayor y un parámetro ∈ a menor que en otro caso. Por tanto, una sociedad con una tasa de homicidios sustancialmente alta será aquella en la cual es más probable que σ / ∈ a > 1. Si esta condición se cumple y si los parámetros χa o λa también son mayores que en una sociedad con una baja o nula tasa de homicidios, entonces podría predecirse lo siguiente: cuando la tasa de homicidios pasa, de manera permanente, de un nivel bajo a uno alto se desatan dos fuerzas de sentido contrario sobre la relación entre el gasto óptimo DJS y el consumo corriente: una de ellas, asociada a los mayores parámetros χa, λa y al menor parámetro ∈ a eleva dicho gasto; otra fuerza, la caída de la riqueza permanente ocasionada por la mayor criminalidad, lo reduce. Para superar esta incertidumbre vamos a considerar que σ / ∈ a es igual a 1. Así, la condición 5a quedará reducida a: (5b) Carlos Esteban Posada - Francisco González66 Una de las diferencias sustanciales con el caso en el cual sólo hay delitos contra la riqueza física es que ahora deberíamos suponer que cuanto mayor es la tasa de criminalidad permanente (medida por δ 0 ), mayor debería ser el parámetro χa, es decir, mayor debería ser el peso que cada miembro (no criminal) de la sociedad ha de dar a los gastos en seguridad en su función de utilidad: (6) Reemplazando 6 en 5b resulta que: (7) Por tanto, un aumento de la tasa de criminalidad (por una sola vez pero que se juzgue permanentemente) tendrá el siguiente efecto sobre la proporción óptima entre el gasto DJS y el consumo: En el lado derecho de la igualdad todos los términos son positivos, excepto uno, χa(δ 0 )γ 1 , si γ 1 es negativo. Por tanto se puede decir que la respuesta óptima de la sociedad ante un aumento permanente de la criminalidad, aun si tal aumento lleva a que los miembros de ella le otorguen un peso mayor a la seguridad en sus funciones de utilidad, podría ser la reducción, en términos relativos, del gasto DJS si el componente inducido de eficiencia de tal gasto fuese negativo y tuviese un peso relativamente grande. Pero si el componente inducido de eficiencia es relativamente pequeño debemos esperar que la respuesta de la sociedad ante el aumento de la criminalidad sea la elevación del gasto DJS. De otra parte, las ecuaciones 5a y 7 hacen evidente, de nuevo, algo que ya se había mencionado: que todo incremento del componente EL G A S T O EN D EF EN S A , J U S T I C I A Y S E G U R I DA D 67 autónomo de eficiencia del gasto DJS (γ 0 ) aumenta la relación entre el gasto DJS y el consumo. 4. SIMPLIFICACIONES Y JUSTIFICACIONES El modelo expuesto tiene, entre varias simplificaciones, cuatro que vale la pena examinar y justificar: 1. La protección la puede ofrecer también, como una mercancía específica, el sector privado. Aunque eso es cierto, y usual en el caso colombiano, habría que anotar que el modelo hace abstracción de los gastos privados menores en protección y disuasión (como los de celaduría y vigilancia, blindaje, etc.), sólo para simplificar el análisis, y considera que los gastos privados mayores (la compra de “para-militarismo”, etc.) hacen parte de la actividad criminal, y que lo que soporta el sector privado no criminal como una pérdida material y humana es el resultado neto de la acción criminal, es decir, neto de bajas eventuales entre diferentes grupos criminales rivales. El supuesto básico detrás de lo anterior es el siguiente: la oferta privada (descentralizada) de protección y disuasión entraña externa- lidades negativas para la sociedad en su conjunto que impiden generar un grado de seguridad que sea una situación de equilibrio estable y equivalente o superior, desde el punto de vista de alcanzar un óptimo de Pareto23, a la del monopolio público de la oferta de protección y disuasión. Esta es una hipótesis central de la teoría clásica del Estado. 2. El modelo no identifica un actor criminal con un sujeto racional con un objeto a maximizar y con restricciones. La defensa frente a esta crítica sería la siguiente: un modelo que suponga que el grueso de la acción criminal la ejerce un oligopolio liderado por un agente racional, con quien el representante de la sociedad civil pudiese entrar en un juego estratégico, generaría, entre sus conclusiones, una que también se deriva del presente modelo: existe un nivel óptimo de gasto DJS que puede aumentar en función de los mayores riesgos de acciones criminales o de la mayor eficiencia de este gasto. Esto es cierto a menos que se suponga que el gasto DJS tiene un efecto perverso: elevar la capacidad y voluntad de agresión del criminal24. Pero si esto no se supone, a mayor capacidad protectora y disuasiva del gasto DJS mayor podría ser la recompensa que derive la sociedad de un eventual “juego estratégico” con el enemigo. 23. Situación en la cual ya no se puede aumentar la utilidad de algún agente sin reducir la de otro. 24. El efecto perverso se podría esperar con criminales dominados por fanatismo ideológico u otros motivos irracionales. Carlos Esteban Posada - Francisco González68 Por tanto, un modelo inmune a esa crítica sólo conduciría a conclusiones similares a las del presentado en estas páginas25. 3. La función de eficiencia del gasto DJS es altamente simplificada (lineal); esto conduce a generar una relación, también lineal, entre el gasto óptimo DJS (como proporción del consumo) y su eficiencia. Sin embargo, la teoría económica sugiere que deberíamos esperar que a partir de ciertos niveles relativamente altos de eficiencia no debería ser óptimo seguir elevando el gasto DJS, a menos que se introdujesen elementos estratégicos como los contemplados en el punto anterior, dados unos crecientes costos de oportunidad de tal acción26. Con todo, creemos (y nos basamos en esta conjetura) que es aceptable la simplificación referida para los rangos de gasto DJS y de criminalidad imperantes en Colombia. 4. La función de utilidad utilizada, aunque es de uso corriente, obliga a suponer que cada avance significativo de la tasa de criminalidad conduce a aumentar la preferencia relativa por seguridad, χ; de lo contrario habría que concluir, gracias a la simplificación de la función de eficiencia del gasto DJS, que cuando avanza la criminalidad se hace óptimo reducir este gasto a menos que γ 1 > 0. Se puede considerar que χ es un índice del costo de oportunidad (por unidad de riqueza esperada) de no tener mayor cobertura contra el riesgo. Así, a mayor riesgo, mayor será el costo de oportunidad de tener sólo el grado de cobertura previo y, por ende, mayor debería ser χ, es decir, mayor la demanda por protección. 5. DATOS E INTERPRETACIONES El gasto real DJS ha estado creciendo al menos desde 1950, y no sólo en términos absolutos sino también con respecto al PIB real, como se observó en la introducción. Tras un ascenso entre 1950 y 1955 (probablemente por la llamada “Violencia”) y otro entre 1958 y 1971 (la época del “Frente Nacional”), se permitió su descenso hasta 1977; posteriormente ha crecido hasta alcanzar un pico en 1997: 4.64% del PIB27. 25. Sin embargo, los modelos económicos del secuestro, un crimen que se relaciona con una expectativa de negociación, requieren identificar al criminal como un actor racional y describir un juego estratégico (Lapan y Sandler 1988, y Mejía 2000). 26. Una de las posibles razones de un creciente costo de oportunidad del gasto DJS podría ser una eficiencia marginal decreciente de éste. 27. Cifras de ejecución presupuestal (diferentes a las de caja) e incluyen gastos en cabeza del Ministerio de Justicia, Fiscalía, Rama Judicial, Policía y Defensa EL G A S T O EN D EF EN S A , J U S T I C I A Y S E G U R I DA D 69 Desde mediados o fines de los años 70 el crecimiento del gasto DJS ha sido mayor que el de otros componentes del consumo público y mayor que el del consumo privado, así que su participación en el consumo ha aumentado (gráfico 5.1). Gráfico 5.1: Dentro de este gasto los componentes de mayor crecimiento han sido los destinados a seguridad y justicia. Con respecto a la situación imperante a mediados de los años setenta, el gasto de menor crecimiento ha sido el clasificado en el rubro “Policía” (gráfico 5.2). Gráfico 5.2: Nacional; fuente: Contraloría General de la República. En Granada (1997) se encuentra una historia de los acontecimientos políticos, sociales y de orden público que han acompañado el ascenso del gasto en defensa y seguridad en Colombia entre 1950 y 1994. Clavijo (1998, cap. VII) realiza otra descripción sobre el asunto para el período 1950-98. Giha et al. (1999) analizan la composición interna del gasto militar en Colombia desde 1980. Carlos Esteban Posada - Francisco González70 ¿Cómo explicar, entonces, el aumento del gasto DJS? De acuerdo con el modelo previamente expuesto, el aumento de la tasa de criminalidad tiene efectos ambiguos sobre la relación entre los niveles óptimos del gasto DJS y del consumo. En efecto, dicho aumento desata fuerzas que llevan, unas, a aumentarlas y, otras, a reducirla. Pero bajo algunos supuestos simplificadores, como se hizo evidente en secciones anteriores, el aumento de la criminalidad tiende a elevar tal relación. Y esto es tanto más cierto si, como se ha observado en la realidad colombiana, el aumento de la criminalidad se ha concentrado en delitos contra la vida. De otra parte, el aumento del grado de eficiencia autónoma del gasto DJS, si se juzga permanentemente, siempre tiende a incrementar el nivel de gasto. Las cifras que pueden servir para medir la eficiencia del gasto DJS no siempre están fácilmente disponibles o, en algunos casos, no parecen lo suficientemente nítidas o, incluso, confiables28. En los gráficos 5.3, 5.4 y 5.5 se presentan unos indicadores alternativos de eficiencia del gasto DJS que se lograron construir con estadísticas de dominio público. Los indicadores de eficiencia son, claro está, bastante burdos y, además, deben interpretarse como indicadores de eficiencia parcialmente endógena, relativa y en el margen. Para aclarar el punto del margen se podría pensar, por ejemplo, que si el gasto DJS no fuese marginal sino sustancialmente menor que el observado hoy, digamos sólo la tercera parte del que actualmente se ejecuta, probablemente el grado de criminalidad sería bastante mayor que el observado, en promedio, en los últimos quince años, además de que tendríamos un nivel de seguridad externa mucho más precario. Un primer grupo de indicadores podría denominarse de “eficiencia intrínseca” porque se basan total o parcialmente en categorías del procedimiento penal29. 28. Un análisis de los criterios e indicadores de eficiencia del gasto público en defensa, justicia y seguridad se encuentra en González y Posada (2000). Una limitación grande del análisis siguiente, como ya se había mencionado, es que no separa el gasto en defensa externa (que no tiene relación con delitos) de los otros componentes del gasto en defensa, seguridad y justicia. Otra limitación es que no separamos los componentes fijos o imposibles de modificar en el corto plazo del gasto DJS, como los pagos de pensiones, de los componentes controlables. 29. El número utilizado para denominar cada indicador es irrelevante. Se construyeron con información publicada por el DANE (1995) y, en algunos casos, con información del Minjusticia, Consejo Superior de la Judicatura e Instituto de Medicina L egal. La información contenida en DANE-Ministerio de Justicia (1996) es compatible con la presentada en este documento. Indicadores más o menos semejantes a los que presentamos aquí han sido utilizados en otros trabajos; véase, por ejemplo, Ramos y Garrido (1995), Montenegro y Posada EL G A S T O EN D EF EN S A , J U S T I C I A Y S E G U R I DA D 71 Eficiencia Descripción intrínseca 1 Sentencias (penales) condenatorias / sumarios iniciados 2 Resoluciones de acusación / providencias de calificación 3 Personas aprendidas / delitos con iniciación de sumario Tabla 5.1: Tipos de eficiencia intrínseca Gráfico 5.3: Estos indicadores se definen en la tabla 5.1 y sus magnitudes se presentan en el gráfico 5.330. Antes de continuar conviene hacer una descripción que ayude a entender la razón por la cual esos indicadores se refieren a eficiencia intrínseca. El procedimiento penal tiene tres grandes etapas: la etapa de iniciación de sumarios; la de calificación, que da lugar a las siguientes vías alternativas: resolución de acusación, cesación de procedimiento, preclusión de la investigación, reapertura de la investigación, sobreseimiento temporal o definitivo y archivo; y la etapa de sentencia (o de sentencias ejecutoriadas); a su turno la etapa (1995) y Clavijo (1997 y 1998, cap. VIII). Uno de los análisis que utiliza un mayor número de indicadores de eficiencia de la justicia (tanto intrínsecos como extrínsecos, incluyendo de impunidad) es el de Clavijo (1998, cap. VIII). En Echeverry y Partow (1998) se encuentran indicadores por departamentos del país. 30. Salvo aclaración, la fuente es DANE (1995), así: sentencias condenatorias: cuadro 4.3.4.1, sumarios iniciados: cuadro 4.3.1.3; resoluciones de acusación y providencias de calificación: cuadro 4.3.3.1; aprendidos cuadro 5.2.2.3, y delitos con iniciación de sumario: cuadro 4.3.2.3. La cifra de aprendidos según Minjusticia y C.S.J fueron suministradas por el DNP. Carlos Esteban Posada - Francisco González72 de sentencia tiene tres vías alternativas: sentencia condenatoria, sen- tencia absolutoria y fallo inhibitorio31. Tal como se observa en el gráfico 5.3. los indicadores de eficiencia intrínseca no son constantes a través del tiempo; sus movimientos pueden estar indicando que el componente inducido o endógeno de eficiencia cambia con cada nivel de criminalidad. Pero es evidente que desde mediados de los años 80 y hasta principios de los noventa aumentaron, reflejando, posiblemente, un esfuerzo social conducente a aumentar la eficiencia autónoma del gasto DJS. No obstante, un segundo tipo de indicadores narra una historia distinta. Este segundo grupo podría denominarse de eficiencia “extrínseca” porque no se atiene a categorías del procedimiento penal y, aunque es muy burdo, apunta directamente a un componente grave de criminalidad: los homicidios. El principal, entre estos indicadores, es la relación entre personas capturadas por las autoridades y el número de homicidios reportados por la Policía (gráfico 5.4)32. Gráfico 5.4: 31. En Clavijo (1998, cap. VIII), Ramos y Garrido (1995) se encuentran descripciones del ordenamiento institucional de la rama judicial y de los procedimientos conducentes a las decisiones y fallos judiciales; además presentan indicadores de eficiencia específicos de la rama judicial. Clavijo (idid.) explica la reforma jurídica ordenada por la Constitución de 1991 en materia penal (el sistema acusatorio en cabeza de la Fiscalía, etc.), sus razones, alcances previsibles y su impacto sobre el gasto público en justicia. 32. El número de homicidios según la Policía es reportado por el DANE (1995) en cuadro 5.2.2.6 pero es distinto al número de defunciones por homicidio (reportado en el mismo cuadro del DANE) según clasificación de la Organización Mundial de Salud. EL G A S T O EN D EF EN S A , J U S T I C I A Y S E G U R I DA D 73 La historia que narran los indicadores mencionados parece ser la siguiente: tras un estancamiento o una caída de la eficiencia del gasto DJS hasta mediados de los años 80 (probablemente por causa de una mayor criminalidad), la sociedad parece haber hecho esfuerzos por revertir tal tendencia, que se tradujeron en ascensos de algunos indicadores de “eficiencia intrínseca” pero no en uno muy importante, referido a “eficiencia extrínseca”, la relación entre el número de personas aprehendidas y el número de homicidios. Un último indicador lo denominamos “ineficiencia aparente”, pues simplemente relaciona el número total de delitos con el monto total del gasto en DJS, medido éste en millones de pesos constantes (gráfico 5.5). Gráfico 5.5: Vistos los indicadores de manera conjunta, y teniendo en cuenta también la evolución del número de delitos totales y del correspon- diente a homicidios (gráficos 1.1 y 1.2), surge la siguiente conjetura: probablemente está aumentando la eficiencia del aparato policial- judicial para combatir y disuadir la comisión de delitos diferentes a homicidios y secuestros33, como por ejemplo los relativos a patrimonio, administración pública, violencia en el seno de la familia, abuso sexual, etc., pero no ha aumentado significativamente la eficiencia del aparato estatal para combatir los asesinatos (y secuestros), si se compara la situación actual con la vigente a principios de los años 70, cuando el país estaba en vísperas de soportar el inicio de la gran oleada de asesinatos ocurrida entre 1975 y 1995. 33. El número de secuestros aumentó a lo largo de todo el decenio de los noventa (Mejía, 2000). Carlos Esteban Posada - Francisco González74 6. RESUMEN Y CONCLUSIONES El gasto público real en defensa, justicia y seguridad (gasto DJS) ha estado creciendo desde finales de los años 70 no sólo en términos absolutos sino como proporción del PIB y del consumo privado. Tal ascenso se puede entender, al menos parcialmente, como una respuesta óptima ante el aumento de la criminalidad, sobre todo de la concentrada en homicidios (y secuestros), de acuerdo con deter- minados parámetros del modelo presentado en este artículo. Una de las implicaciones más interesantes del modelo es la siguiente: los incrementos autónomos de la eficiencia del gasto en DJS (esto es, las mejoras de eficiencia que surgen de mayores esfuerzos de los miembros del Estado, y que no se derivan simplemente de reducciones ex ante de la criminalidad) causan un aumento del nivel óptimo de tal gasto. Así, el modelo puede entenderse como una explicación detallada de las condiciones bajo las cuales es impertinente suponer la existencia de un trade-off entre nivel y eficiencia del gasto DJS. Por tanto, según este mismo modelo, si la eficiencia del gasto en DJS se estanca o decrece podría no ser óptimo continuar elevando tal gasto. Y no hay evidencia contundente de que la eficiencia de este gasto haya aumentado significativamente en los últimos 10 años en lo que se refiere a los delitos contra la vida y la libertad individual. De ser correcto lo anterior, y si quisiera reducir sustancial y permanentemente la tasa de homicidios intencionales (y secuestros), la sociedad civil debe aceptar mayor nivel de gasto DJS si observa más eficiencia de éste. REFERENCIAS BIBLIOGRÁFICAS Blanchard, Oliver. 1985. “Debt, Deficits, and Finite Horizons”, Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 93, Nº 21. Blanchard, Oliver; Stanley Fischer. 1989. Lectures on Macroeconomics, MIT Press. Clavijo, Sergio. 1997. “Situación de la justicia en Colombia: incidencia sobre el gasto público e indicadores de desempeño”, Justicia y Desarrollo. Debates, Nº 1 (agosto). Clavijo, Sergio. 1998. Política Fiscal y Estado en Colombia, Uniandes. Davoodi, Hamid; Benedict Clements; Jerald Schiff y Peter Debaere. 1999. “Military Spending, the Peace Dividend, and Fiscal Adjustment”, IMF Working Paper ( WP/99/87), julio. DANE; Ministerio de Justicia y del Derecho. 1996. La justicia colombiana en cifras. 1937-94. Ec he verr y, Juan Car los; Z einab Par tow. 1998. “ W hy Justice is unresponsive to crime: the case of cocaine in Colombia”, Borradores Semanales de Economía (B. de la R.), Nº 87. EL G A S T O EN D EF EN S A , J U S T I C I A Y S E G U R I DA D 75 Ehrlich, Isaac. 1973. “Participation in Illegitimate Activities: A Theore- tical and Empirical Investigation”, Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 81, Nº 3. Fajnzylber, Pablo; Daniel Lederman y Norman Loayza. 1998. Deter- minants of Crime Rates in Latin America and the World. The World Bank, Washington. Gaitán, Fernando. 1995. “Una indagación sobre las causas de la violencia en Colombia”, Dos ensayos especulativos sobre la violencia en Colombia, Fonade-DNP. Gaviria, Alejandro. 2000. “Increasing returns and the evolution of violent crime: the case of Colombia”, Journal of Development Economics, Vol. 61. Giha, Janeth; Héctor Riveros y Andrés Soto. 1999. “El gasto militar en Colombia: aspectos macroeconómicos y microeconómicos”, Revista de la CEPAL, Nº 69 (separata, diciembre). González, Francisco; Carlos Esteban Posada. 2000. “Criminalidad, vio- lencia y gasto público en defensa, justicia y seguridad en Colombia”, documento no publicado (disponible a pedido). Granada, Camilo. 1997. “La evolución del gasto en seguridad y defensa en Colombia, 1950-1994”, Reconocer la guerra para construir la paz, CEREC-Uniandes. Gupta, Dipak. 1990. The Economics of Political Violence, Praeger. Lapan, Harvey; Todd Sandler. 1988. “To Bargain or Not to Bargain: That Is The Question”, American Economic Review, Vol. 78, Nº 2. Mejía, Daniel. 2000. “El secuestro en Colombia: una aproximación económica en un marco de teoría de juegos”, Coyuntura Económica, (próxima aparición). Montenegro, Armando; Carlos Esteban Posada. 1995. “Criminalidad en Colombia”, Coyuntura Económica, Vol. XXV, Nº 1. Montenegro, Armando; Carlos Esteban Posada; Gabriel Piraquive. 2000. “ Violencia, criminalidad y justicia: otra mirada desde la economía”, Coyuntura Económica, (próxima aparición). Posada, Carlos Esteban. 1994. “Modelos económicos de la criminalidad y la posibilidad de una dinámica prolongada”, Planeación y Desarrollo, Vol. XXV. Ramos, Jorge; Daira Garrido. 1995. “Gasto estatal y administración de justicia en Colombia”, Borradores semanales de economía (B. de la R.), Nº 45. Rubio, Mauricio. 1999. Crimen e impunidad, Tercer Mundo-CEDE. Sandler, Todd; Keith Hartley. 1995. The Economics of Defense, Cambridge University Press. work_4rrkxjcwdjbzlgcrpc3x55iqja ---- Punish and The History of Sexuality (Vol. 1); there is also reference to the importance of studying political events and a return to empiricism in political thought. Hannah Arendt stands as the only woman in the text, and while Roy T. Tsao does justice to her work, it is unfortunate that once again her affair with Heidegger is mentioned. Once again the theme of ideology is covered by Tsao’s analysis of Arendt’s The Origins of Totalitarianism; Arendt’s thesis is that a Totalitarian ‘movement’ is one in which all government functions are subordinated ‘to the momentary aims of the movement’s all-embracing ideologyyand the attraction of the movements lay in those masses’ longing to escape from human reality into the sheer fiction of ideology’ (p. 171). As Carver and Martin point out, ‘Unlike the Anglo-American tradition of thought, with which they are commonly contrasted, Continental ideas are routinely derided for being too ‘‘poetic’’, needlessly convoluted and hence dangerously removed from ‘‘common sense’’’ (p. 3). Of course brilliant scholars such as Arendt in Life of the Mind describe poetry as a ‘sign of genius’ and she also makes the point that common sense is on the opposing side of a war between it and reason. Thus ‘If we enter into their spirit and consider their enduring value or contemporary resonances, we may find ourselves trans- formed, or at very least informed, in a way we hadn’t expected’ (p. 3), the book certainly reaches this goal. This was not only a highly informative and engaging read that has provided me with fresh perspectives on old friends and introduced me to new ones, it was also an exciting page turning journey through thought. I would recommend that those with an interest in political theory or political philosophy consider Palgrave Advances in Continental Political Thought. Alex Karolis University of Canberra, Canberra, Australia Justice Beyond Borders Simon Caney Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2006, 319pp. ISBN: 0 19 829350 X. Contemporary Political Theory (2008) 7, 222–224. doi:10.1057/palgrave.cpt.2007.15 The book has two purposes: to present a cosmopolitan global political theory and to critique three rival theoretical approaches (realism, nationalism and the society-of-states tradition). Caney meets both purposes by examining six central Book Reviews 222 Contemporary Political Theory 2008 7 issues of controversy: universalism, civil and political justice, distributive justice, political structures, just war and humanitarian intervention. In each case he argues for cosmopolitan solutions to the moral and theoretical problems raised and refutes arguments offered by the rival traditions. Caney devotes a chapter to each of his six issues. Chapter 2 reassesses the debate between moral relativists and moral universalists. After rejecting some common objections to relativism, Caney presents his own argument for universalism which refers us to properties that he deems are shared by all human beings, such as basic needs. He then claims that if there are valid moral principles concerning these properties — which he assumes there are — then they must apply universally, since it is logical to suppose that ‘valid moral principles apply to all those who are similar in a morally relevant way’ (p. 36). Chapter 3 argues for an extensive list of civil and political human rights. In so doing it confronts two groups of doubters: those that deny there are any human rights and those, such as Rawls, who argue for a more minimal list than the full liberal package. Caney finds the former group motivated by unfounded fears: that rights impose uniformity or engender selfishness. The latter group he deems guilty of two counts of illogic. First, failing to show why foreigners should not be entitled to the same rights that citizens of liberal states are entitled to. Second, failing to recognize the connections between the minimal rights they argue for and the more extensive rights they argue against. Chapter 4 contends that global distributive justice demands the application of four principles: subsistence rights, equality of opportunity, equal pay for equal work and priority for the worst off. Caney’s argument is once again founded on a consistency claim: principles applying domestically should apply globally unless there is good reason to maintain a double standard. He explores arguments defending a double standard made by realists and nationalists and finds them wanting. Chapter 5 argues for cosmopolitan institutions such as a directly elected second assembly at the UN, reformed financial institutions and a strengthened International Court of Justice. Such institutions, he claims, are demanded both on democratic — or what he calls ‘rights-based’ — grounds of giving people a voice in decisions that affect their ability to exercise their rights and the ‘instrumental’ grounds of realizing the principles of justice set out in the previous two chapters (pp. 158–159). Caney goes on to argue, against society- of-states theorists, that the state system cannot act as an adequate alternative to cosmopolitan institutions and, against nationalists, that many of the claims made for national self-determination are too strong. Chapter 6 argues for a just war theory based on the concept of individual rights. A just cause for war is the defence of a political regime that respects its citizens rights or at least does a better job than the attacking regime would do in its place. Caney thus rejects Walzer’s account of jus ad bellum that ties just Book Reviews 223 Contemporary Political Theory 2008 7 cause to the right of states to self-government. One criticism Caney makes of Walzer is that his principles of jus ad bellum and jus in bello fail to logically relate. By contrast Caney argues that principles of jus in bello should be based upon the same concern for individual rights that motivate his principles of jus ad bellum. It is out of respect for the rights of non-combatants that Caney argues they should not ordinarily be targeted. However since Caney’s theory of rights is consequentialist he (controversially) permits the targeting of non-combatants when necessary ‘to protect the rights of a larger group of non- combatants’ (p. 214). Chapter 7 makes an argument for humanitarian intervention also based on individual rights. A just intervention, Caney claims, will defend individual rights against states that, having failed to respect their citizens’ rights, ‘lack moral standing’ (p. 234). He confronts standard arguments against humani- tarian intervention — for instance, that it violates self-government and destroys international stability — but accepts the need for a number of preconditions before a state has a moral, let alone legal, right to intervene. Cosmopolitans are often criticized for utopianism. Perhaps there is no more reason to fault cosmopolitans for holding high ideals than there is to fault political practice for failing to realize them. Nevertheless one pleasing aspect of Caney’s work is he makes cosmopolitan policies seem genuine possibilities. He does so by engaging with the sorts of empirical debates normative philosophers rarely touch. For instance, using the example of the Tobin tax, Caney disputes the claim that every state need cooperate with liberal practices for progress to nevertheless be made (p. 138). On a related point: Caney’s attention to international relations literature makes Justice Beyond Borders a book for IR scholars, as much as for political theorists. Some might complain that the book tries to cover too many topics. Caney anticipates this criticism and in defence points to the extent to which his topics interrelate (pp. 20–21). In any case the criticism would only be apt if the quality of the book’s content suffered as a result of its breadth. This is plainly not the case. The book is rich in detail and insight. Caney moves systematically through the material sorting bad arguments from good while formulating each with impressive clarity. Indeed, the book’s comprehensiveness is actually its primary virtue. Even in the case of familiar arguments, we learn so much simply from Caney’s careful positioning of each point within an overall structure. It is like finally being handed a map of the theoretical landscape. And since few landscapes are as crowded or complex as global political theory, Justice Beyond Borders is a map I do not advise anyone addressing this subject to go without. Kieran Oberman St Cross College, Oxford, UK Book Reviews 224 Contemporary Political Theory 2008 7 Justice Beyond Borders work_4sg725ksgzexpgfn7zmi3vilna ---- TOPIA: Canadian Journal of Cultural Studies | UTP Journals Cookies & Privacy This site uses cookies for analytics and access management. For more information, view our Privacy Policy. Please accept our Terms and Conditions before using our website. Learn more. Skip to Main Content (Press Enter) Cart   |  Renew   |  Help  |   ? Sign in  |  Register ☰ HOME BROWSE PUBLICATIONS ABOUT US About University of Toronto Press Copyright & Permissions Ethics and Publication Malpractice Open Access Awards SUBSCRIBE Subscribe or Renew Online Subscriber Resources The Collection 2021 Catalogue (PDF) RESOURCES For Authors For Librarians For Subscribers Frequently Asked Questions PUBLISH WITH US Partner with Us Call for Papers CONTACT US ☰ Journal Menu Journal Menu ☰ Current Issue Browse Issues COVID-19 Essays Subscribe About Editorial Board Aim & Scope Abstracting & Indexing Permissions Publication Ethics and Malpractice Advertising For Authors Submission Guidelines Open Access Books for Review Recommend Search in: This Journal Anywhere Citation Advanced Current Issue Browse Issues COVID-19 Essays Subscribe About Editorial Board Aim & Scope Abstracting & Indexing Permissions Publication Ethics and Malpractice Advertising For Authors Call for Papers Submission Guidelines Open Access Books for Review Recommend ☰ Journal Menu Home > TOPIA: Canadian Journal of Cultural Studies > List of Issues TOPIA: Canadian Journal of Cultural Studies ISSN: 1206-0143; eISSN: 1916-0194 Online from: January 1, 1997 Frequency: Twice a year TOPIA's mandate is to provide a venue for critical research in cultural studies in Canada and beyond. TOPIA publishes original, peer-reviewed research and theoretical essays on culture that are accessible to a wide readership in the humanities and social sciences. Areas of research relevant to this mandate include the historical, institutional and aesthetic formation of Canadian and postcolonial culture; indigenous studies; cultural memory; and environmental cultural studies. TOPIA publishes two issues per year and is available by subscription in print and online. Current Issue All Issues Most Read Available Content Available Issues Forthcoming Volume 41 Vol. 41, Fall 2020: Special Issue on Our COVID Conjuncture: Critical Essays on the Pandemic; Guest Editors: Penelope Ironstone and Greg Bird (pp. 5-198). Volume 40 Vol. 40, Spring 2019 (pp. 5-147). Volume 39 Vol. 39, Spring 2018: Black Lives, Black Politics, Black Futures (pp. 5-221). Volume 38 Vol. 38, Fall 2017 (pp. 5-208). Volume 37 Vol. 37, Spring 2017 (pp. 5-246). Volume 36 Vol. 36, Fall 2016 (pp. 7-231). Volume 35 Vol. 35, Spring 2016 (pp. 27-235). Volume 34 Vol. 34, Fall 2015 (pp. 6-156). Volume 33 Vol. 33, Spring 2015 (pp. 7-267). Volume 32 Vol. 32, Fall 2014 (pp. 21-346). Volume 30-31 Vol. 30-31, Fall 2013/Spring 2014 (pp. 262-332). Volume 29 Vol. 29, Spring 2013 (pp. 183-219). Volume 28 Vol. 28, Fall 2012: Out of the Ruins, the University to Come (pp. 5-315). Volume 27 Vol. 27, Spring 2012 (pp. 5-318). Volume 26 Vol. 26, Fall 2011 (pp. 5-216). Volume 25 Vol. 25, Spring 2011 (pp. 5-279). Volume 23-24 Vol. 23-24, Spring 2010 (pp. 9-456). Volume 22 Vol. 22, Fall 2009 (pp. 5-246). Volume 21 Vol. 21, Spring 2009 (pp. 5-251). Volume 20 Vol. 20, Fall 2008 (pp. 5-256). Volume 19 Vol. 19, Spring 2008 (pp. 5-212). Volume 18 Vol. 18, Fall 2007 (pp. 11-182). Volume 17 Vol. 17, Spring 2007 (pp. 5-178). Volume 16 Vol. 16, Fall 2006 (pp. 5-176). Volume 15 Vol. 15, Spring 2006 (pp. 5-163). Volume 14 Vol. 14, Fall 2005 (pp. 5-142). Volume 13 Vol. 13, Spring 2005 (pp. 5-187). Volume 12 Vol. 12, Fall 2004 (pp. 5-158). Volume 11 Vol. 11, Spring 2004 (pp. 5-208). Volume 10 Vol. 10, Fall 2003 (pp. 1-122). Volume 9 Vol. 9, Spring 2003 (pp. 3-130). Volume 8 Vol. 8, Fall 2002 (pp. 1-137). Volume 7 Vol. 7, Spring 2002 (pp. 1-131). Volume 6 Vol. 6, Fall 2001 (pp. 1-128). Volume 5 Vol. 5, Spring 2001 (pp. 1-121). Volume 4 Vol. 4, Fall 2000 (pp. 5-120). Volume 3 Vol. 3, Spring 2000 (pp. 7-120). Volume 2 Vol. 2, Spring 1998 (pp. 11-119). Volume 1 Vol. 1, Spring 1997 (pp. 7-108). SUBMIT To submit your article to TOPIA, please click the link above to our online submission site. Connect with the Journal Top Articles Most Recent Most Read Most Cited Volume: 41, pp. 5-10 Our COVID Conjuncture: Critical Essays on the Pandemic Penelope Ironstone and Greg Bird Volume: 41, pp. 11-12 The New Normal Victor Li Volume: 41, pp. 13-21 COVID-19: An Essay in Keywords Penelope Ironstone See More Volume: 40, pp. 5-14 Still Here Christina Sharpe Volume: 16, pp. 23-49 Multiculturalism, Racism and Infectious Disease in the Global City: The Experience of the 2003 SARS Outbreak in Toronto Roger Keil and Harris Ali Volume: 39, pp. 29-47 Reading Black Resistance through Afrofuturism: Notes on post-Apocalyptic Blackness and Black Rebel Cyborgs in Canada Robyn Maynard See More Volume: 36, pp. 43-57 From a Fishy Place: Examining Canadian State Law Applied in the Daniels Decision from the Perspective of Métis Legal Orders Zoe Todd Volume: 12, pp. 25-40 Second-hand Shaman: Imag(in)ing Indigeneity from Le Jeune to Pratt, Moore and Beresford Sam W. McKegney Volume: 25, pp. 5-28 To Hear the Whistle Blow: Technology and Politics on the Battle River Branch Line Darin Barney See More Subscription Options Institutional Offers TOPIA Volume 43-44 (online only): $105.00 TOPIA Volume 43-44 (print and online): $172.00 UTP Collection About the Collection (online only): $4310.00 UTP Collection About the Collection (print and online): $4905.00 TOPIA Archive Volumes 1-40 (online only): $1580.00 Individual Offers TOPIA 1-Year (online only): $55.00 TOPIA 1-Year (print and online): $95.00 TOPIA Newsletter Sign Up FEEDBACK Your name Email Message UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO PRESS Journals Division ABOUT UTP Journals List of Journals Copyright & Permissions Publication Ethics & Malpractice Open Access Publish with Us Contact Us RESOURCES Resource Centre FAQ Authors Librarians Subscribers Site Help Site License Agreement (PDF) UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO PRESS UTP Books UTP Distribution UofT Bookstore Job Opportunities Environmental Policy Privacy Policy Accessibility Policy © 2021 University of Toronto Press Powered by Atypon® Literatum   work_4wbfrpbd6fazles77wqqnbohzi ---- NQHR 2014-02.indb Netherlands Quarterly of Human Rights, Vol. 32/2, 183–213, 2014. © Netherlands Institute of Human Rights (SIM), Printed in the Netherlands. 183 FOREGROUNDING SOCIO-ECONOMIC RIGHTS IN TRANSITIONAL JUSTICE: REALISING JUSTICE FOR VIOLATIONS OF ECONOMIC AND SOCIAL RIGHTS Amanda Cahill-Ripley* Abstract: Transitional justice has traditionally ignored or sidelined violations of economic and social rights, focussing on violations of civil and political rights as the primary grave human rights violations to be addressed when seeking justice for past atrocities. Th is paper explores the omission of these rights from the fi eld and uncovers the shortcomings of such an approach. It will argue that there is a need for transitional justice to address both deliberate violations of economic and social rights resulting from confl ict or repression, but also structural violations which have acted as root causes of confl ict within the State. It is submitted that past experiences of prosecutorial and restorative justice illustrate that violations of economic and social rights have been acknowledged as background information rather than primary concerns for transitional justice. In conclusion it is contended that economic and social rights need to be brought to the foreground of transitional justice processes in order to ensure eff ective transitional justice which refl ects the needs and rights of the local population, and addresses the root causes of confl ict, thus preventing confl ict reoccurring around the same sources. Th e inclusion of economic and social rights concerns within transitional justice mechanisms will therefore contribute to a more holistic and inclusive transitional justice process. Keywords: confl ict; economic, social and cultural rights; international criminal law; peacebuilding; social justice; structural violence; transitional justice; truth commissions * Amanda Cahill-Ripley is Lecturer in Law at Lancaster University, UK and Visiting Lecturer in Human Rights Law at the University of Bergen, Norway. Contact a.cahill@lancaster.ac.uk. Amanda Cahill-Ripley 184 Intersentia 1. INTRODUCTION Transitional justice has traditionally ignored or sidelined violations of economic and social rights, focussing almost entirely on violations of civil and political rights as the primary grave human rights violations to be addressed when seeking justice for past atrocities.1 Whilst selected authors have addressed the at times confl icting aims of ‘justice’ and ‘peace’,2 very little attention has been given to the consequences for peace and justice if violations of economic and social rights are either completely ignored, are relegated to secondary concerns or are presented as ‘background’ information, that is information which is setting the context for what are perceived as more serious violations of civil and political rights. Whilst violations of economic and social rights may seem to be of a lesser gravity than those of civil and political rights (such as the right to life and freedom from torture), socio-economic rights violations can constitute gross human rights violations. Some examples may include the burning and destruction of homes and crops; the poisoning of water; forced evictions; deliberately induced starvation and displacement leading to lack of housing, water and food, subsequent ill health and disease, lack of education and employment and in the worst cases human deaths. Moreover, such violations may be more widespread and systematic. For instance, in the confl ict in Timor-Leste it was noted that far more people were aff ected by economic and social rights violations than civil and political rights violations.3 Th e displacement of people from their villages, farms and traditional settlements resulted in severe violations of the rights to food, health, housing, education, self-determination 1 Offi ce of the High Commissioner for Human Rights, Analytical study on human rights and transitional justice (United Nations 2009) A/HRC/12/18 para 59; International Council on Human Rights Policy, Negotiating Justice? Human Rights and Peace Agreements (International Council on Human Rights Policy 2006) 101; Lisa Laplante, ‘Transitional Justice and Peace Building: Diagnosing and Addressing the Socioeconomic Roots of Violence through a Human Rights Framework ’ (2008) 2 Th e International Journal of Transitional Justice 331, 333; L. Waldorf, ‘Anticipating the Past: Transitional Justice and Socio-Economic Wrongs’ (2012) 21(2) Social and Legal Studies 171, 173. 2 Hurst Hannum, ‘Peace versus Justice: Creating Rights as well as Order out of Chaos’ (2006) 13(4) International Peacekeeping 582; N. Roht-Arriaza and J. Mariezcurrena (eds), Transitional Justice in the 21st century – Beyond Truth versus Justice (Cambridge University Press 2006); I. Zartman and V. Kremeniuk (eds), Peace Versus Justice: Negotiating Forward- and Backward-looking Outcomes (Rowman and Littlefi eld 2005); Ellen L. Lutz, Eileen F. Babbitt, and Hurst Hannum, ‘Human Rights and Confl ict Resolution from the Practitioners’ Perspectives’ (2003) 27(1) Th e Fletcher Forum of World Aff airs 173; C. Lekha Sriram and S. Pillay (eds) Peace Versus Justice?: Th e Dilemmas of Transitional Justice in Africa (James Currey Publishers 2010); P. Schulz, Peace Versus Justice?: Th e International Criminal Court (ICC) in Africa (VDM Publishing 2011). 3 Th e Commission for Reception, Truth and Reconciliation in Timor-Leste, Chega! Th e Report of the Commission for Reception, Truth and Reconciliation in Timor-Leste (CAVR) (Commission for Reception, Truth and Reconciliation 31  October 2005) Executive Summary 74; ch 7.9: Economic and Social Rights. Foregrounding Socio-Economic Rights in Transitional Justice Netherlands Quarterly of Human Rights, Vol. 32/2 (2014) 185 of resources and freedom of movement.4 Th ese economic and social rights violations were directly attributable to the confl ict. In addition, violations of economic and social rights can act as confl ict triggers.5 As the International Council on Human Rights Policy notes, ‘[…] socio-economic issues oft en lie at the core of confl icts, and are particularly implicated in the transitional period, when reconstruction of war-torn societies must take place’.6 As such, ignoring violations of such rights is a risk both to the peace process and the eff ectiveness of justice mechanisms during transition. Th e Editors of Th e International Journal of Transitional Justice note, Our preoccupation with justice aft er civil upheaval seems to outstrip our attention to preventing or attending to the systematic injustices – economic, social and political – that fuel the causes that erupt into paroxysms of violence. We have an international criminal court to prosecute war criminals, yet millions of civilians are deprived of adequate water, nutrition and healthcare […]. Th ere is a conspicuous absence of international accountability for these injustices.7 Th is paper will explore this omission of economic and social rights from transitional justice. It will examine possible reasons for the limited attention or indeed exclusion of these rights and uncover the shortcomings of such an approach. It will investigate whether there is a need to redefi ne transitional justice, to embrace a holistic conception of justice8 inclusive of ideas of social justice including therefore justice for violations of economic, social and cultural rights. It will argue that the recognition of these rights within transitional justice mechanisms will make transitional justice more eff ective in responding to the needs of the people, fi rstly by seeking remedy for deliberate and direct violations of economic and social rights but also by addressing violations of these rights which have acted as root causes of confl ict, thus helping to prevent confl ict reoccurring around the same sources. Further, if human rights are truly indivisible and interdependent violations of civil and political rights cannot be addressed eff ectively in times of transition unless corresponding and related violations of economic and social rights are also addressed. Th e inclusion of economic and social rights concerns within transitional justice mechanisms will therefore contribute to a more holistic and inclusive transitional justice process. 4 Ibid. 5 Offi ce of the High Commissioner for Human Rights (n 2); E. Schmid, ‘Liberia’s Truth Commission Report: Economic, Social and Cultural Rights in Transitional Justice’ (2009) XXIV Praxis – Th e Fletcher Journal of Human Security 5, 6; S.C. Agbakwa, ‘A Path Least Taken: Economic and Social Rights and the Prospects of Confl ict Prevention and Peacebuilding in Africa’ (2003) 47(1) Journal of African Law 38, 40; Laplante (n 1) 334–335. 6 International Council on Human Rights Policy (n 1) 101. 7 Editorial, (2012) 6(1) International Journal of Transitional Justice (IJTJ) 6. 8 A. Boraine, ‘Transitional Justice: A Holistic Interpretation’ (2006) 60(1) Journal of International Aff airs 17, 17. Amanda Cahill-Ripley 186 Intersentia Th e defi nition of transitional justice is contested: One frequently quoted defi nition is provided by Roht-Arriaza, who defi nes transitional justice as ‘a set of practices, mechanisms and concerns that arise following a period of confl ict, civil strife or repression, and that are aimed directly at confronting and dealing with past violations of human rights and humanitarian law’.9 However, as Arbour argues, Transitional justice must have the ambition to assist the transformation of oppressed societies into free ones by addressing the injustices of the past through measures that will procure an equitable future. It must reach to – but also beyond – the crimes and abuses committed during the confl ict that led to the transition, and it must address the human rights violations that pre-dated the confl ict and caused or contributed to it. With these aims so broadly defi ned, transitional justice practitioners will very likely expose a great number of discriminatory practices and violations of economic, social, and cultural rights.10 With such variety in the interpretation of what transitional justice is, the fi rst section of the paper will examine current defi nitions of transitional justice and explore the reasons why economic and social rights have been largely excluded from the fi eld. Th is will include an investigation of the notion of justice inherent in transitional practices. Second, the author will examine previous examples of transitional justice mechanisms to explore how they have dealt with violations of economic and social rights. Th is will include consideration of prosecutorial methods such as international tribunals and the International Criminal Court (ICC) and an investigation of restorative methods such as truth and reconciliation commissions. Cases explored include South Africa, Liberia, Sierra Leone and Timor-Leste. Th ese particular cases have been selected as limited examples where the Commissions have considered economic and social rights in some way. Finally there will be a discussion on how to expand and develop the concept and practice of transitional justice to incorporate these rights, including off ering proposals for improvement drawn from good practice and identifying continuing challenges to this process. 2. WHY IS THERE A LACK OF ECONOMIC AND SOCIAL RIGHTS WITHIN ‘TRADITIONAL’ TRANSITIONAL JUSTICE? 2.1. THE ‘NARROW’ DEFINITION OF TRANSITIONAL JUSTICE It is submitted that ‘Traditional’ transitional justice consists of prosecutorial justice, such as tribunals and trials, where the focus is on establishing accountability, 9 Roht-Arriaza and Mariezcurrena (n 2) 2. 10 L. Arbour, ‘Economic and Social Justice for Societies in Transition’ (2007) 40(1) International Law and Politics 1, 3. Foregrounding Socio-Economic Rights in Transitional Justice Netherlands Quarterly of Human Rights, Vol. 32/2 (2014) 187 responsibility and punishment for crimes. It also consists of mechanisms of restorative justice, although the concept of ‘restorative justice’ is limited in this discussion to truth and reconciliation commissions.11 Th is mechanism focuses on the idea of ‘truth telling’ as allowing reconciliation. Th e above mechanisms are judicial or quasi- judicial and their primary mandate is to deal with mass and grave violations that have occurred during the confl ict in question. However, very little consideration has been given to economic and social rights within these mechanisms. Th ere are several reasons for this. One reason for the omission (or very limited consideration) of such rights to date is simply because economic and social rights are not seen as within the remit of transitional justice. Th is argument is dependent on how transitional justice is defi ned and what the role of transitional justice is believed to be. Transitional justice has many defi nitions,12 and arguments have been put forward for it to include, for instance, justice for economic crimes, development concerns and local and community-based approaches to justice and reconciliation.13 However, it remains overwhelmingly concerned with criminal prosecutions and truth commissions in relation to civil and political rights violations. Olsen defi nes transitional justice as ‘the array of processes designed to address past human rights violations following periods of political turmoil, state repression, or armed confl ict’.14 Olsen notes ‘Human rights violations are defi ned as extrajudicial killings, disappearances, torture and arbitrary arrest and imprisonment’ only.15 Two signifi cant factors are apparent with this defi nition. First, the focus is purely on past violations, and, second, on violations of civil and political rights alone – not economic and social rights. Th is defi nition could be considered illustrative of the prevalent traditional concept of transitional justice which has dominated the fi eld until recently.16 2.2. ECONOMIC AND SOCIAL RIGHTS – NOT LEGAL RIGHTS A further reason why transitional justice both in theory and in practice has tended to omit or severely limit consideration of economic and social rights is the familiar 11 Other mechanisms such as reparations and institutional reform can be considered a part of restorative justice. For example see T. Olsen, L. Payne and A. Reiter, Transitional Justice in Balance – Comparing Processes, Weighing Effi cacy (US Institute of Peace Press 2010) 12. However, in terms of traditional transitional justice, the focus has been very much on truth commissions. 12 For example see International Centre for Transitional Justice (ICTJ), Fact Sheet ‘What is Transitional Justice?’ (ICTJ 2009) at , last accessed 14  June 2013; P. Arthur, ‘How Transitions Reshaped Human Rights: A Conceptual History of Transitional Justice’ (2009) 31(2) Human Rights Quarterly 321; C. Bell, ‘Transitional Justice, Interdisciplinarity and the state of the “Field” or “Non-Field”’ (2009) 3(1) International Journal of Transitional Justice 5; R. Teitel, ‘Th eoretical and International Frameworks – Transitional Justice in a New Era’ (2002) 26 Fordham International Law Journal 893; Arbour (n 10); and Olsen et al (n 11). 13 Editorial (n 7) 1–10. 14 Olsen et al, (n 11) 11. 15 Ibid, 11 original footnote 10. 16 Editorial (n 7) 6. Amanda Cahill-Ripley 188 Intersentia argument that these rights are not ‘real’ or ‘legal’ rights or at best constitute secondary rights – general aims to be achieved progressively as the ideal standard.17 Th is view contributes to the argument that economic and social rights are also non-justiciable.18 Th e traditional conception of transitional justice has focussed upon grave violations of civil and political rights as the only justiciable rights that can be tried in a court of law. Th erefore, if economic and social rights are not viewed as justiciable rights they cannot be incorporated within this traditional model of transitional justice. Th is argument is also a consequence of the dependence within the fi eld on a criminal justice model (see below). Moreover, there remains a general lack of understanding on the part of scholars and practitioners within the fi eld of transitional justice as to what economic and social rights are. For example, scholars have equated such rights with economic policy or development plans rather than comprehending them as distinct and discrete legal entitlements with a legally defi ned scope and normative content.19 2.3. THE IDEA OF CRIMINAL JUSTICE V OTHER NOTIONS OF JUSTICE A third and related argument is that socio-economic rights have been omitted from transitional justice mechanisms because of the focus on criminal justice.20 Th ese mechanisms have relied on defi nitions of justice based in criminal law rather than utilising diff erent conceptions of justice, for example, social justice. Th is is also due to the dominance of prosecutorial forms of justice.21 Arbour has noted, ‘As transitional justice is heavily inspired by mainstream justice and criminal law, its neglect of economic, social, and cultural rights is merely symptomatic of a deep ambivalence within justice systems about social justice’.22 One explanation for this ambivalence towards social justice is the plethora of defi nitions surrounding the concept. Social justice has been defi ned as anything from distributive justice to equality of opportunity.23 Consequently, the idea of social justice has been largely excluded from the law as either an empty concept with little substance (for example, equality of opportunity) or as a radical concept such as redistributive justice, which can confl ict with liberal ideals of human rights and is ideologically and fi nancially unacceptable to many States. However, it is not necessarily undesirable to utilise the concept of social 17 Arbour (n 10) 11; D. Sharp, ‘Addressing Economic Violence in Times of Transition: Toward a Positive- Peace Paradigm for Transitional Justice’ (2012) 35 Fordham International Law Journal 780, 797. 18 R. Carranza, ‘Plunder and Pain: Should Transitional Justice Engage with Corruption and Economic Crimes?’(2008) 2 Th e International Journal of Transitional Justice 310, 315. 19 For an example of such an approach see Waldorf (n 1). 20 Waldorf (n 1) 173. 21 Olsen et al (n 11) 12. 22 Arbour (n 10) 5. 23 Ibid, original footnote 10. Foregrounding Socio-Economic Rights in Transitional Justice Netherlands Quarterly of Human Rights, Vol. 32/2 (2014) 189 justice as a basis for expanding our ideas of what transitional justice should include, namely economic and social rights, but that in order to do so we need to defi ne what we mean by social justice. Th e following defi nition put forward by Louise Arbour is useful: Social justice refers to minimum legal standards guaranteeing substantive equality (as refl ected in international human rights instruments prohibiting discrimination and protecting economic, social, and cultural rights) in the fulfi lment of the idea of freedom from want. Substantive equality is important to social justice, as equality with no qualifi cation may be misinterpreted as formal equality or equality of opportunities only.24 Th is conception of social justice can be defi ned as ‘substantive social justice’, where violations of economic and social rights can be seen as an element of social injustice. Th erefore, acknowledging and seeking remedy for these violations can be seen as a form of achieving substantive social justice which could be incorporated into transitional justice. Moreover, the link between such rights and social justice is not a new idea.25 Indeed, in the context of poverty alleviation, Williams notes that poverty is ‘the absence of basic justice for a specifi c person or groups of persons as a condition of severe material deprivation’ where justice is the ‘formal, impartial and consistent application of specifi c rules in relation to rights such as the rights to equality, human dignity, […] housing, healthcare, food, water, social security, [and] education […]. Th e protection and enforcement of these rights would constitute substantive justice’.26 It is evident that violations of economic and social rights have been ignored or sidelined within transitional justice as they are not viewed as a legitimate concern for prosecutorial justice or are deemed too diffi cult an issue for criminal accountability. Rather they can be viewed as an element of social justice which has been excluded from the fi eld. Th e dependency of transitional justice on criminal justice models has also been critiqued in terms of a general lack of eff ectiveness. Bell notes, ‘the demands of communities do not start and end with the punishment of individuals […] mechanisms for dealing with the past respond also to demands for truth which cannot be delivered by traditional criminal models’.27 24 Arbour (n 10). 25 See A. Sen, Th e Idea of Justice (Penguin 2009); J. Rawls, A Th eory of Justice (Belknap Press 1971 Reprint 2005); M. Nussbaum, ‘Capabilities as Fundamental Entitlements: Sen and Social Justice’ (2003) 9(2–3) Feminist Economics 33; and K. Kallen, Social Inequality and Social Injustice – A Human Rights Perspective (Palgrave Macmillan 2004). 26 J. Williams, ‘Poverty: A Human Rights Violation in Post-Apartheid South Africa’ in T. Pogge (ed), Freedom from Poverty as a Human Right – Th eory and Politics (Vol.2) (UNESCO 2010) 321, 345. 27 C. Bell, Peace Agreements and Human Rights (Oxford University Press 2000) 289. Amanda Cahill-Ripley 190 Intersentia 2.4. ECONOMIC AND SOCIAL RIGHTS AS BACKGROUND INFORMATION Th e overwhelming focus on notions of criminal justice coupled with the argument that socio-economic rights are not legal justiciable rights has resulted in an omission of these rights from the traditional remit of prosecutorial justice. However, how have restorative justice mechanisms such as truth commissions dealt with economic and social rights? It is fi rst important to consider what the purpose of a truth commission is. Olsen states that a truth commission should ‘attempt to bring justice by working toward a new inclusive society that addresses the fundamental needs of the population’.28 Th ere is a clear development in remit from prosecutorial justice in that a truth commission should attempt to look to the future, not just deal with past abuses in isolation (if this is indeed possible). However, how can the ‘fundamental needs of the population’ be addressed without addressing economic and social needs (rights) as well as civil and political rights? Attempting to address violations of civil and political rights without addressing related violations of economic and social rights undermines the indivisibility of human rights and does not take into account their interdependence. For example, if someone has been forcibly displaced, their home burnt down and their access to food denied and they subsequently die from starvation and exposure, this would constitute a violation not just of the right to life but also the rights to food, housing and health. Moreover, the failure to address violations of economic and social rights impacts upon the remedy for violations of civil and political rights. For instance, if someone has been subjected to inhumane treatment and is off ered rehabilitation as one form of reparation this will be of limited eff ect if they have no home or no long term sustainable means to support themselves to enjoy an adequate standard of living. Th erefore, for a truth commission to fulfi l this wider mandate it will need to consider economic and social rights as well as civil and political rights. Evidence to date suggests that traditionally truth commissions have also limited their consideration of human rights abuses to violations of civil and political rights.29 Where truth and reconciliation commissions have considered socio-economic rights they have tended to consider them as evidence of the wider context of the confl ict.30 Deliberate and direct grave violations have been presented as secondary information, either as supporting evidence of wider conditions of confl ict-induced poverty or as background information to explain the context in which civil and political rights’ violations have taken place. Exceptionally, a very small number of truth commissions have attempted to address socio-economic rights in a limited manner noting for example that they can be causal factors of confl ict. Th ese few cases are examined 28 Olsen et al (n 11) 12. See also International Council on Human Rights Policy, ‘Aim of a Truth Commission’, (n 1) 80. 29 Lisa Laplante, ‘On the Indivisibility of Rights: Truth Commissions, Reparations and the Right to Development’ (2007) 10 Yale Human Rights and Development Law Journal 141, 142. 30 Sharp (n 17) 793–794. Foregrounding Socio-Economic Rights in Transitional Justice Netherlands Quarterly of Human Rights, Vol. 32/2 (2014) 191 shortly but an illustrative example can be seen in the case of South Africa, where economic and social problems have been a major consequence of the apartheid system.31 During the mandate of the South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission (SATRC) violations of economic and social rights were seen purely as contextual information for narrowly defi ned gross human rights violations.32 Hence, these violations remained in the background of the SATRC rather than being a central concern of the body. 2.5. THE NATURE AND SCOPE OF ECONOMIC AND SOCIAL RIGHTS VIOLATIONS Th e idea of economic and social rights as contextual information can be seen as closely linked to the problematic issue of dealing with transition in countries which prior to the confl ict had pre-existing violations of economic and social rights or, at the very least economic and social conditions which threatened the enjoyment of such rights by sectors of society (due to discrimination and inequality). Whilst in some cases it will be easy to identify specifi c acts of violence against individuals and communities that constitute grave violations of economic and social rights, in other cases these violations will be a result of structural and endemic violence and repression by the State, for example the former apartheid system in South Africa. Th is raises the question of whether transitional justice should include consideration of historical injustices within a State or consider only limited episodes of violence.33 If the latter is true this may have an impact on economic and social rights violations that are a result of structural violence and structural injustices that pre-date the confl ict or which may have helped instigate it.34 Structural violence exists when the structures of the State support the unequal distribution of power (and agency) which is reinforced through unequal distribution of resources.35 Th us structural violence based upon this ‘unequal distribution of power then systematically disadvantages those who do not hold as much if any power at all’.36 Examples of such structural violence can include racial inequality, poverty and institutionalised discrimination. Moreover, the link between structural violence and violations of economic and social rights is clear. Ho notes that ‘When economic and social structures conspire to limit one’s agency to 31 Ibid. 32 South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission, Truth and Reconciliation Commission of South Africa Report Vol. 5, Chapter 1 Analysis of Gross Violations of Human Rights (South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission 1998) 11, para 48. 33 Editorial (n 7) 3. 34 Sharp (n 17) 802. 35 For a defi nition and discussion of the meaning of structural and or institutional and indirect violence see J. Galtung, ‘Violence, Peace, and Peace Research’ (1969) 6(3) Journal of Peace Research 167, 170. See also P. Farmer, Pathologies of Power (University of California Press 2005). 36 K. Ho, ‘Structural Violence as a Human Rights Violation’ (2007) 4(2) Essex Human Rights Review 1, 4. Amanda Cahill-Ripley 192 Intersentia the extent that fundamental human needs cannot be met then structural violence becomes a structural violation of human rights’.37 Th us, the perceived diffi culty with outlining the scope and nature of socio- economic rights violations to be considered by transitional justice bodies is a further reason why such violations have been sidelined within the discipline. Nevertheless, these structural socio-economic violations can cause both frustration and unrest which in turn can drive confl ict. If there is no attempt to address these structural and societal inequalities then the risk is that confl ict will resurface despite eff orts to address more direct violations of economic and social rights within transitional justice mechanisms. As such, there is a question to be answered as to how these mechanisms can address not only grave violations of such rights that have taken place as a deliberate and direct result of the confl ict, but also systematic and structural violations of economic and social rights that act as an ongoing source of injustice and root cause of the confl ict itself. Laplante notes, ‘presenting socioeconomic root causes of confl ict as historical context leaves policy change to the discretion of political leaders, while presenting them as rights violations makes redress and reform a political imperative’.38 3. WIDER AND DEEPER TRANSITIONAL JUSTICE As previously stated, in the past, dominant thinking and practice in transitional justice has focussed on addressing civil and political rights violations that have occurred during the confl ict and measures to deal with the past. Th is can be deemed ‘traditional’ transitional justice. However, the International Centre for Transitional Justice39 provides a more progressive defi nition of transitional justice: ‘Transitional justice is a response to systematic or widespread violations of human rights. It seeks recognition for the victims and to promote possibilities for peace, reconciliation and democracy […]’.40 Th e focus remains on ‘systematic and widespread’ violations of human rights, but the nature of violations is not defi ned. As such, in theory it does not exclude violations of economic and social rights. Furthermore, the defi nition clearly characterises transitional justice as responsive to past events (as in the previous defi nition) but also as having a positive role in the future with the phrase: ‘promote possibilities for peace, reconciliation and democracy […]’. One could argue that clearly transitional justice must include responding to grave violations of economic and social rights (as well as civil and political rights violations) that have occurred in the past but also that promoting possibilities for peace needs to include measures 37 Ibid 15. 38 Laplante (n 1) 341. 39 Hereinaft er referred to as ICTJ. 40 International Centre for Transitional Justice (n 12). Foregrounding Socio-Economic Rights in Transitional Justice Netherlands Quarterly of Human Rights, Vol. 32/2 (2014) 193 to prevent further violations of economic and social rights, including addressing underlying inequality, discrimination and poverty. Boraine has called for a ‘holistic interpretation’ of transitional justice;41 while not detracting from criminal justice, this approach ‘off ers a deeper, richer and broader vision of justice’.42 McEvoy and McGregor also argue for ‘thicker transitional justice’ – a move away from strict legalism to include other aspects of justice necessary for transition to peace.43 Consequently, a broader and more holistic defi nition of transitional justice can be envisaged, which would include traditional mechanisms with a mandate to investigate and seek remedy for grave violations of both economic and social rights and civil and political rights. Th is would bring economic and social rights fi rmly to the foreground of traditional mechanisms and would constitute the fi rst step in the development of a wider and deeper remit for transitional justice. Furthermore, wider and deeper transitional justice should be considered an integral element of peacebuilding. Such transitional justice might encompass measures (some of which may have previously been seen as a concern for peacebuilding) that are less legalistic and look to the future as well as deal with the past. Th ese could include, for example, recommendations for legal reforms and protections such as bills of rights and other constitutional guarantees,44 as well as a rights-based approach to development,45 institutional reform46 and institution building, including the establishment of new institutions to monitor economic and social rights such as a national human rights institution.47 Such an approach to transitional justice has been seen as ‘shift ing the paradigm’ from one of transition to one of transformation (transformative justice).48 Conversely, this wider and deeper approach to transitional justice has been challenged. Waldorf notes that whilst transitional justice is struggling to deliver on its ‘original promises of truth, justice and reconciliation’ more demands are being 41 Boraine (n 8). 42 Ibid 18. 43 K. McEvoy and L. McGregor, (eds), Transitional Justice From Below: Grassroots Activism and the Struggle for Change (Hart 2008). 44 OHCHR (n 1) para.63. 45 McEvoy and McGregor (n 44) 33–37; See also P. De Greiff and R. Duthie (eds), Transitional Justice and Development – Making Connections (Social Science Research Council 2009); R. Mani, ‘Editorial – Dilemmas of Expanding Transitional Justice, or Forging the Nexus between Transitional Justice and Development’ (2008) 2 Th e International Journal of Transitional Justice 253. 46 C. Sandoval Villalba, Transitional Justice: Key Concepts, Processes and Challenges, Institute for Democracy and Confl ict Resolution Briefi ng Paper (IDCR-BP-07/11) (IDCR/University of Essex 2011). See also Offi ce of the High Commissioner for Human Rights, Rule of Law Tools for Post- Confl ict States: Truth Commissions, (United Nations 2006). 47 See A. Cahill-Ripley, From Peace Agreements to Post-Confl ict Reconstruction: Economic and Social Rights and Peacebuilding (forthcoming article, on fi le with author). 48 See Sharp (n 17) 804. See also M. Evans, ‘Land, socio-economic rights and transformative justice’, Paper presented at Land Divided: Land and South African Society in 2013, in Comparative Perspective conference (University of Cape Town, 24–27 March 2013). Amanda Cahill-Ripley 194 Intersentia placed on it.49 Moreover, Mani states that it is diffi cult to see how remedy for such broadly encountered social injustice could be incorporated into ‘targeted’ transitional justice measures.50 Waldorf argues that despite increasing calls for a broadening of the remit for transitional justice, it should be ‘short-term, legalistic and corrective’ and, as such, should focus on gross violations of civil and political rights alone.51 Practical diffi culties, he notes, include infl ating public expectations of transitional justice mechanisms, the existing limited fi nancial capacity of mechanisms and the long-term nature of dealing with economic and social rights violations. However, it is argued that the limited fi nancial capacity of any transitional justice mechanism is relevant to investigation and remedy of any human rights violations whether civil and political rights or economic and social rights. For example, it may take many years for a functioning tribunal to bring war criminals to justice whether they have committed grave violations of civil and political rights or economic and social rights. In terms of fi nancial costs of reparations programmes, a reparations programme for individual victims of torture may cost just as much as communal reparations to provide adequate housing. Th e decision as to how best to limit the capacity and funding of a transitional justice mechanism should be based upon the nature and scope of the violations encountered as well as ‘a careful analysis of the drivers of confl ict’, not on an arbitrary distinction between civil and political rights violations and socio-economic rights violations.52 Questions of time, money and expertise are relevant for all human rights considerations. Further, as Schmid notes, the challenges of competing demands, resource constraints and high expectations are not unique to the inclusion of economic and social rights within transitional justice but are challenges encountered more widely in the entire process of peacebuilding within post-confl ict reconstruction of a State.53 Waldorf argues that the remedy for violations of economic and social rights should be a matter for ‘democratic politics and distributive justice’.54 However, this view of economic and social rights perceives them not as legal entitlements but as social aims or policy goals and supports the view previously presented that such rights have been ignored precisely because they are not conceived of as legal rights. Th is illustrates a fundamental misunderstanding of what economic and social rights are. Economic and social rights cannot be equated with development or broad economic policies. Th ey are discrete and justicable legal entitlements with a legally defi ned scope, normative content and correlative obligations.55 49 Waldorf (n 1) 172. 50 R. Mani (n 45) 255. 51 Waldorf (n 1) 179. 52 Sharp (n 17) 805. 53 Schmid (n 5) 17–18. 54 Waldorf (n 1) 179; Schmid (n 5) 17–18. 55 Th ere are many sources which provide for economic, social and cultural rights within international human rights law, constitutional provisions and national legislation. However, the main Foregrounding Socio-Economic Rights in Transitional Justice Netherlands Quarterly of Human Rights, Vol. 32/2 (2014) 195 Moreover, Waldorf ignores the fact that violations of such rights are oft en a result of deliberate violent acts carried out during confl ict seeming to suggest instead that socio-economic rights violations are solely due to poverty and/or inequality. Th is is clearly not the case. Many direct and deliberate violations of economic and social rights take place within confl ict as noted previously. Furthermore, even if certain violations of economic and social rights are a result of inequality and discrimination, this is likely to have been exacerbated by the confl ict and needs to be addressed. Both structural violations of economic and social rights and direct violations of economic and social rights are human rights violations – they are not simply ‘under development’ as suggested. Moreover, he argues that the ‘reduction of longstanding inequality is necessarily post-transitional’56 but it is not clear when the transitional period ends and the post-transitional period begins. If, as Waldorf seems to suggest, inequality is left unchecked whilst in transition, it is diffi cult to see how this would contribute to the goal of justice. Without tackling inequality there can only be partial or limited justice and the seeds of future confl ict remain. As Sharp argues, transitional justice cannot be just and meaningful if a ‘signifi cant portion of the drivers of confl ict and resulting violations of international law are pushed to the side’.57 Waldorf argues that to include economic and social rights within the remit of transitional justice is casting the net too wide.58 However, the argument that diversifying the remit of transitional justice results in a weakening of these mechanisms is not borne out in practice. In fact, the opposite may be true. Carranza argues that the effi cacy of these mechanisms is actually enhanced by the inclusion of economic and social rights as the process is more holistic and with less room for gaps in addressing the needs of the population.59 Another challenge to the inclusion of economic and social rights within transitional processes is the implicit assumption that if we include these rights then we ‘dilute’ the seriousness of grave violations of civil and political rights, that is, by recognising violations of economic and social rights it would somehow diminish the gravity of mass violations and severe crimes such as genocide. Th is assumption may be based on the historical view of economic and social rights as secondary rights of a lesser importance or not real rights, as mentioned previously. It is not suggested, for example, that lack of housing due to confl ict can be equated with genocide. However, starving people to death through deliberate blocking of food aid as seen in Zimbabwe,60 or forced displacement as experienced in Timor-Leste,61 can be as international instrument is the UN International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (adopted 16 Dec 1966, entered into force 3 Jan 1976) 993 UNTS 14531 (ICESCR). 56 Waldorf (n 1) 179. 57 Sharp (n 17) 805. 58 Waldorf (n 1) 179. 59 Carranza (n 18) 322. 60 Rhoda Howard-Hassmann, ‘Mugabe’s Zimbabwe, 2000–2009: Massive Human Rights Violations and the Failure to Protect’ (2010) 32(4) Human Rights Quarterly 898. 61 Th e Commission for Reception, Truth and Reconciliation in Timor-Leste, Forced Displacement and Famine, National Public Hearing, 28–29 July 2003 (CAVR 2005). Amanda Cahill-Ripley 196 Intersentia severe as crimes against humanity or war crimes of direct violence. Moreover, they may constitute such crimes in and of themselves.62 It is evident therefore that in the fi rst instance transitional justice mechanisms need to recognise that gross violations of human rights include severe and systematic violations of economic and social rights63 and that such bodies establish a mandate for dealing with such violations. In addition, transitional justice mechanisms also need to recognise that some economic and social rights violations may be the result of more structural violence endemic in the State and/or region. 4. EXPERIENCES TO DATE – WHAT CAN WE LEARN FROM PAST PRACTICE? Within academia researchers have begun to explore a broader mandate for transitional justice;64 some authors have considered the role of ‘economic crimes’,65 others the link between transitional justice and development.66 In practice, however, States in transition from confl ict or repression continue to choose criminal prosecutions and truth commissions as the primary methods for seeking justice for human rights abuses.67 Th erefore, the fi rst step to foregrounding economic and social rights within transitional justice is for these violations to be considered as genuine breaches of the relevant law68 and as legitimate concerns for traditional mechanisms, both prosecutorial and restorative. It is therefore important to examine the past practice of both prosecutorial justice mechanisms and restorative justice mechanisms to assess how they have dealt with economic and social rights violations and to draw upon any examples of good practice for future integration of such rights within these processes. 62 See L. van den Herik, ‘Economic, Social and Cultural Rights – International Criminal Law’s Blind Spot’ (2013) Grotius Centre Working Paper 2013/002-ICL (University of Leiden 2013). 63 Offi ce of the High Commissioner for Human Rights, Commission On Human Rights, Study concerning the right to restitution, compensation and rehabilitation for victims of gross violations of human rights and fundamental freedoms, Final report submitted by Mr. Th eo van Boven, Special Rapporteur (2 July 1993) E/CN.4/Sub.2/1993/8 para 12 notes that gross violations of human rights ‘frequently eff ect’ economic, social and cultural rights. 64 I. Muvingi, ‘Sitting on Powder Kegs: Socioeconomic Rights in Transitional Societies’ (2009) 3 International Journal of Transitional Justice 163; Waldorf (n 1); Arbour (n 10). 65 Z. Miller, ‘Eff ects of Indivisibility: In Search of the “Economic” in Transitional Justice’ (2008) 2 International Journal Transitional Justice 266; Carranza (n 18). 66 For example see De Greiff and Duthie (n 45); Mani (n 45); and Laplante (n 29) 141–177. 67 See Editorial (n 7) 1. 68 Whether deemed a crime or a human rights violation under International human rights law, international criminal law, international humanitarian law, refugee law and relevant domestic provisions. Foregrounding Socio-Economic Rights in Transitional Justice Netherlands Quarterly of Human Rights, Vol. 32/2 (2014) 197 4.1. PROSECUTORIAL FORMS OF JUSTICE AND ECONOMIC AND SOCIAL RIGHTS Th e focus of prosecutorial forms of transitional justice within international law has been on mechanisms based upon the framework of international criminal law.69 Th ese measures usually take the form of an international court such as the International Criminal Court (ICC) or a tribunal set up for a specifi c State / confl ict such as the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia (ICTY). Although the legal basis for such courts and tribunals includes provisions which can be applied to violations of economic and social rights it is evident that in the majority of these processes there has been little or no consideration of such rights violations as a part of wider gross human rights violations or as crimes in their own right. When considering the law there are clearly international criminal law provisions which could apply to such gross violations of socio-economic rights,70 but very little attention has been given to exploring the potential or limitations of this area of the law to deal with such violations.71 Th e Offi ce of the High Commissioner for Human Rights’ Analytical study on human rights and transitional justice states that ‘International criminal tribunals have investigated and prosecuted cases of violations of economic, social and cultural rights, stating that, the ICTY has recognized that the widespread destruction of homes and property may constitute a crime against humanity’.72 Furthermore, they note the case of Prosecutor v. Kupreskic et al.,73 where the Trial Chamber found that […] attacks on property can constitute persecution. […] comprehensive destruction of homes and property. Such an attack on property in fact constitutes a destruction of the livelihood of a certain population. Th is may have the same inhumane consequences as a forced transfer or deportation. Moreover, the burning of a residential property may oft en be committed with recklessness towards the lives of its inhabitants. Th e Trial Chamber therefore concludes that this act may constitute a gross or blatant denial of fundamental human rights, and, if committed on discriminatory grounds, it may constitute persecution.74 69 In this instance I do not discuss other mechanisms such as national courts established for transitional justice purposes. 70 For example, under the International Criminal Court Rome Statute, Art 8 (2) (b) (xxv) starvation as a weapon of war is a specifi c crime, however to date no one has been indicted on this charge. Other possible provisions include ICC Rome Statute, Article  7 (1) (b) Crime against humanity of extermination; Article  7 (1) (h) Crime against humanity of persecution, Article  8 (2) (a) (iii) War crime of wilfully causing great suff ering; Article  8 (2) (a) (iv) War crime of destruction and appropriation of property; Article 8 (2) (b) (ii) War crime of attacking civilian objects; ICC Rome Statute, Article  6(c) by deliberately infl icting conditions of life calculated to bring about physical destruction. 71 Van den Herik (n 62). 72 Offi ce of the High Commissioner for Human Rights (n 2) para.61. 73 Prosecutor v Kupreskic et al (Judgment) ICTY, IT-95–16-T (14 January 2000) paras 628–631. 74 Ibid para. 631. See also Prosecutor v Stanislav Galić (Judgment) ICTY, IT-98–29-T (5  December 2003) para.42 and Prosecutor v Blaskić (Judgment) ICTY, IT-95–14-T (3 March 2000) where damage Amanda Cahill-Ripley 198 Intersentia However, despite this acknowledgement that economic and social rights violations can constitute crimes under international criminal law, these violations are not explicitly recognised as violations of economic and social rights. Rather, ‘the broad crime defi nitions of persecution and crimes against humanity off er some leeway to “import” socio-economic human rights notions’75 into a criminal law framework. Although this illustrates a positive development in that such violations are explicitly addressed as possible of constituting gross violations of human rights under international criminal law, it remains disappointing that the explicit identifi cation of such crimes as economic and social rights violations remains an omission. As van den Herik notes ‘there is no direct criminalisation of socio-economic rights, but rather a pronounced appreciation of the socio-economic dimensions of crimes’.76 It is also the case that in other trials at the ICTY, despite evidence of severe economic and social rights violations, these acts were relegated to the role of background contextual information for civil and political rights violations as constitutive of international crimes. For example, in Prosecutor v. Dragomir Milošević,77 the Trial Chamber held that the siege of Sarajevo was ‘characterised by a persistent attack or campaign over a period of fourteen months, during which the civilian population was denied regular access to food, water, medicine and other essential supplies, and deprived of its right to leave the city freely at its own will and pace’.78 However, the trial did not note any violations of economic and social rights as an element of either crimes against humanity or unlawful attacks against civilians. More generally, the deliberate starvation of civilians and burning and destruction of homes was widely documented as evidence to form a picture of the wider context in which violations of personal integrity rights took place. Th ese violations of economic and social rights have not been acknowledged as such nor has anyone been indicted for these violations as constituting an element of a crime against humanity or a war crime.79 Likewise, the ICC has not explicitly referred to economic and social rights violations as elements of relevant crimes despite evidence and indictments noting what amounts to severe violations of such rights. For example, in the fi rst warrant to civilian property was seen as an element of an attack on Civilians as a Violation of the Laws or Customs of War as set forth in Article  51 of Additional Protocol I and Article  13 of Additional Protocol II to the Geneva Conventions of 1949) punishable under Article  3 of the Statute of the Tribunal. 75 Van den Herik (n 62) 8. 76 Ibid. 77 Prosecutor v Dragomir Milošević (Judgment) International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia (ICTY) IT-98–29/1-T (12 December 2007). 78 Ibid para 751. 79 Th ere is no specifi c provision under ICTY for a crime of starvation as weapon of war as there is in the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court 1998 Art 8 ICC Art 8 (2)(b)xxv. However the defi nition of crimes against humanity could encompass deliberate starvation. Foregrounding Socio-Economic Rights in Transitional Justice Netherlands Quarterly of Human Rights, Vol. 32/2 (2014) 199 of arrest in Prosecutor v. Omar Hassan Ahmad Al Bashir (Omar Al Bashir),80 the Prosecution submits that GoS (Government of Sudan) forces systematically destroyed the means of survival – including food, shelter, crops, livestock and, in particular, wells and water pumps – of the Fur, Masalit and Zaghawa civilian population in Darfur because “[t]he aim was to ensure that those inhabitants not killed outright would be unable to survive without assistance”.81 In this regard, the Prosecution submits that: Given Darfur’s hostile desert environment and lack of infrastructure, livelihood strategies historically have centred on the village. It is diffi cult to survive outside the communal setting. As an example, ensuring adequate access to water has long been an essential component of livelihood strategies. To facilitate access to water by both humans and animals, many villagers dug communal wells or maintained other communal water sources. Militia/Janjaweed and the Armed Forces repeatedly destroyed, polluted or poisoned these wells so as to deprive the villagers of water needed for survival. In a number of cases, water installations were bombed.82 Th is can clearly be viewed as a severe violation of the rights to food, water and housing as well as constituting elements of crimes against humanity,83 and war crimes.84 Skogly argues that crimes against humanity should include severe violations of economic and social rights.85 Further examples of such economic and social rights violations include deliberate blockage of food aid86 as seen in the 80 Prosecutor v Omar Hassan Ahmad Al Bashir (“Omar Al Bashir”) (International Criminal Court Pre- Trial Chamber I, Decision on the Prosecution’s Application for a Warrant of Arrest against Omar Hassan Ahmad Al Bashir) ICC-02/05–01/09 (4 March 2009). 81 Th e Prosecution Application, para 175(Footnote in original document). 82 Prosecutor v Omar Hassan Ahmad Al Bashir (“Omar Al Bashir”) (International Criminal Court Pre- Trial Chamber I, Decision on the Prosecution’s Application for a Warrant of Arrest against Omar Hassan Ahmad Al Bashir) ICC-02/05–01/09 (4 March 2009) para 91. Original footnote omitted. See also para 93.However, it was also noted that ‘there are no reasonable grounds to believe that such a contamination was a core feature of their attacks,’ 32. 83 In particular, Rome Statute of the ICC, Th e Elements of Crimes, (reproduced from the Offi cial Records of the Assembly of States Parties to the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, First session, New York, 3–10  September 2002, 6, Article  7(1)(b) Crime against humanity of extermination; Elements ‘1. Th e perpetrator killed one or more persons, including by infl icting conditions of life calculated to bring about the destruction of part of a population,’ directly or indirectly and including through depriving access to food and medicines and Article 7(1)(h) Crime against humanity of persecution, Elements, ‘1. Th e perpetrator severely deprived, contrary to international law, one or more persons of fundamental rights.’ 84 Specifi cally Rome Statute of the ICC Article  8(2)(a)(iii) War crime of wilfully causing great suff ering; Article 8(2)(a)(iv) War crime of destruction and appropriation of property (ICC Elements of Crimes page 15); Article  8(2)(b)(ii) War crime of attacking civilian objects (ICC Elements of Crimes, page  18) and Article  8(2)(b)(xxv) War crime of starvation as a method of warfare (ICC Elements of Crimes, page 31). 85 S.I. Skogly, ‘Crimes Against Humanity – Revisited: Is Th ere a Role for Economic and Social Rights?’ (2001) 5(1) Th e International Journal of Human Rights 58, 59. 86 Ibid 69–70. Amanda Cahill-Ripley 200 Intersentia Sudan87 or deliberate State-induced famine as seen in Zimbabwe.88 Th e President of Zimbabwe, Robert Mugabe, deliberately denied international agencies permission to bring food into Zimbabwe to feed the starving. Despite unprecedented food shortages he distributed State-owned grain to his supporters whilst withholding it from opposition supporters.89 Th us, in the period from 2000 to 2009, the policies of the Zimbabwean government can be considered as State-induced famine and as such constitute a crime against humanity under international criminal law.90 Th eir actions can also be viewed as deliberate violations of the right to food, health and housing. Yet, Mugabe has never been indicted for these crimes at the ICC, despite calls for his indictment.91 It is also the case that gross violations of economic and social rights can constitute genocide.92 For example, in the second warrant of arrest Prosecutor v Omar Hassan Ahmad Al Bashir, Bashir has been indicted on the count of genocide by deliberately infl icting conditions of life calculated to bring about physical destruction, within the meaning of article 6(c) of the Statute. Th is includes […] reasonable grounds to believe that in furtherance of the genocidal policy, as part of the GoS’s unlawful attack on the above-mentioned part of the civilian population of Darfur and with knowledge of such attack, GoS forces throughout the Darfur region (i) at times, contaminated the wells and water pumps of the towns and villages primarily inhabited by members of the Fur, Masalit and Zaghawa groups that they attacked.93 Clearly these acts amount to a violation of the right to water as well as the right to life. Th ese examples illustrate the marginalisation of economic and social rights violations within prosecutorial transitional justice mechanisms and more broadly within international criminal law. Van den Herik argues that international criminal law has the potential to capture such large-scale and deliberate socio-economic rights violations but that the ‘rigid legal requirements’ of criminal law results in a marginal role for international criminal processes in addressing such violations. For example, the focus upon commission of acts rather than omission and the strict defi nition of 87 A. de Waal, Famine Crimes: Politics and the Disaster Relief Industry in Africa (Th e International African Institute, in association with James Currey, Oxford and Indiana University Press 1997). 88 Howard-Hassmann (n 60). 89 Ibid 901; 908. 90 Rome Statute of the ICC, Art 7(1)(k). 91 Howard-Hassmann (n 60) 907. 92 Rome Statute of the ICC, Article 6(c) by deliberately infl icting conditions of life calculated to bring about physical destruction. 93 Prosecutor v Omar Hassan Ahmad Al Bashir (“Omar Al Bashir”) (Second Warrant of Arrest against Omar Hassan Ahmad Al Bashir) ICC-02/05–01/09 (12  July 2010) 7. See also footnote in original, Physicians for Human Rights, Report, Darfur Assault on Survival, A call for Security, Justice, and Restitution (Anx J44) DAR-OTP-0119–0635 at 0679 which mentions three incidents of destruction of water sources). Foregrounding Socio-Economic Rights in Transitional Justice Netherlands Quarterly of Human Rights, Vol. 32/2 (2014) 201 crimes and legality principle of the ICC94 leave ‘less space for direct recourse to human rights in the realm of substantive criminal law’.95 However, despite these diffi culties there are, as illustrated, provisions that can accommodate such violations. It is clear that systematic and large scale abuse of such rights can meet the threshold required to constitute a crime against humanity, war crimes or even genocide. Furthermore, to limit such crimes to violations of civil and political rights ‘is an arbitrary limitation that should be challenged’.96 Violations of economic and social rights that are of a severe nature and can be considered under the relevant international criminal law should be the subject of established prosecutorial mechanisms such as international courts and tribunals, just as gross violations of civil and political rights are. Such international courts and tribunals clearly have the capacity to consider economic and social rights violations within existing international criminal law and international humanitarian law, helping to increase the visibility of socio-economic abuses.97 As Schmid argues, there are no legal obstacles in doing so.98 4.2. RESTORATIVE JUSTICE AND ECONOMIC AND SOCIAL RIGHTS (TRUTH AND RECONCILIATION COMMISSIONS) If violations of economic and social rights do not reach the threshold required by international criminal law to be considered under the above noted provisions there is a need for mechanisms to address violations of a less severe nature. A truth commission, for example, can incorporate within their mandate international human rights standards that do not necessarily require such a high threshold to be reached before violations can be considered. With this in mind it may be that restorative justice mechanisms are more appropriate in certain cases for dealing with economic and social rights violations as they can encompass severe and systematic violations of economic and social rights but also those of a lesser gravity.99 Further, they are not subject to the same strict legal modalities of international criminal law. In terms of assessing and examining previous practice, however, there are few examples of truth commissions who have fully engaged with economic and social rights. As stated above, exceptionally a small number have addressed such rights in a limited and incomplete manner. Accordingly, this paper will focus upon the limited cases where the commission have engaged in some way with economic and social rights or have encountered such rights violations as a signifi cant element of the confl ict. 94 Rome Statute of the ICC, Article 22(2). See also Art 21(3). 95 Van den Herik (n 62) 5. 96 Skogly (n 85) 74. 97 Van den Herik (n 62) 18. 98 E. Schmid, ‘War Crimes Related to Violations of Economic, Social and Cultural Rights’ (2011) 71(3) Heidelberg Journal of International Law 523, 540. 99 Offi ce of the High Commissioner for Human Rights (n 1) para 60. Amanda Cahill-Ripley 202 Intersentia 4.2.1. South Africa Th e South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission is probably the most well- known and researched truth and reconciliation commission in the world. However, very little attention has been given to analysing how it dealt with economic and social rights within the transitional justice process. Th e Commission was limited in its mandate by the defi nition of gross human rights violations provided for in the founding legislation which stated, “gross violation of human rights” means the violation of human rights through – (a) the killing, abduction, torture or severe ill treatment of any person; or (b) any attempt, conspiracy, incitement, instigation, command or procurement to commit an act referred to in paragraph (a), which emanated from confl icts of the past and which was committed during the period 1 March 1960 to 10 May 1994 within or outside the Republic, and the commission of which was advised, planned, directed, commanded or ordered, by any person acting with a political motive.100 Th is defi nition limited the attention of the Commission to events which emanated from the confl icts of the past, rather than from the policies of apartheid.101 Whilst it is understandable that the Commission felt it could not undertake responsibility for investigating the entire and extensive aff ects of apartheid, this does not mean that deliberate and gross violations of socio-economic rights could not have been deemed ‘severe ill treatment’ under the existing mandate. Furthermore, the narrow defi nition of human rights violations was not in line with public expectations of the Commission, which was asked to investigate forced evictions and displacement and discrimination in education, work and other economic and social rights violations, especially those faced by women. Th e Commission did hold ‘Institutional and Special Hearings’ relating to inter alia business, the healthcare system and women.102 Th ese hearings noted the structural violence and associated violations as a result of the apartheid system. However, it is disappointing that in its fi nal report the Commission noted that ‘these issues formed part of the broader context within which the specifi cally defi ned gross human rights violations had taken place’.103 Th us, economic and social rights violations were positioned fi rmly in the background, as contextual information. 100 (South Africa) Promotion Of National Unity And Reconciliation Act 34 of 1995, section 1(1)(ix) [defi nition of ‘gross violation of human rights’ amended by s. 21 (a) of act 104 of 1996]. See also South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission, Truth and Reconciliation Commission of South Africa Report 1998, Vol.1 Chapter 4, Defi ning Gross Violations Of Human Rights (South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission 1998) 70–78, paras 82–90. 101 South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission (n 32) para 48. 102 South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission, Truth and Reconciliation Commission of South Africa Report 1998, Vol. 4 Institutional and Special Hearings (South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission 1998). 103 South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission (n 32) paras 48 and 49. Foregrounding Socio-Economic Rights in Transitional Justice Netherlands Quarterly of Human Rights, Vol. 32/2 (2014) 203 Individuals who were a subject of these violations were excluded from recognition as victims and from reparations.104 4.2.2. Liberia Th e Republic of Liberia Truth and Reconciliation Commission had a broad mandate to address all gross violations of human rights, including an explicit reference to economic and social rights but this was qualifi ed by a statement linking these violations to ‘economic crimes’.105 Although the Commission recognised that such violations were a major root cause of the confl ict, noting that poverty, corruption, limited access to education, economic, social, civil and political inequalities and land tenure and distribution, were all contributing factors,106 the Commission failed to translate this recognition of economic and social rights violations into a primary concern for the truth and reconciliation commission. As Schmid notes there is a signifi cant gap between the fi ndings of the Commission in relation to the causes of confl ict and the legal analysis of abuses committed.107 Th e focus instead was on economic crimes – that is on crimes related to corruption that had economic impacts rather than on a rights- based analysis of violations. Th is raises the issue of the diff erences between economic and social rights violations and the concept of economic crimes. In some cases they have been treated as synonymous with one another, however, it is argued that this is not the case. Sharp refers to the concept of ‘economic violence’ but acknowledges that this is a broader concept than purely violations of economic and social rights also including corruption and plunder of natural resources within the defi nition.108 Although the latter have also been sidelined within transitional justice it is important to diff erentiate between economic and social rights violations under international law and the wider crimes which can lead to such violations.109 4.2.3. Sierra Leone Similarly, the Sierra Leone Truth and Reconciliation Commission had a mandate to consider ‘Violations of economic, social and cultural rights as well as of civil and 104 Ibid. 105 Republic Of Liberia Truth and Reconciliation Commission, Final Report Volume One Preliminary Findings and Determinations (Th e Truth and Reconciliation Commission of Liberia 2008) Section ii, 23. 106 Ibid 4, note.2. For the Commission’s defi nition of economic crimes and further discussion see Republic Of Liberia Truth and Reconciliation Commission Final Report Volume Th ree: Appendices, Title III: Economic Crimes and the Confl ict, Exploitation and Abuse (Th e Truth and Reconciliation Commission of Liberia 2009) 2, para 8. 107 Schmid (n 5) 6. 108 Sharp (n 17) 782. 109 Ibid 785. Further research is required on the relationship between economic crimes such as corruption and ESR. Notable publications include Carranza (n 18); and Schmid (n 5) 19. Amanda Cahill-Ripley 204 Intersentia political rights, as well as other categories of rights such as the right to development and the right to peace’.110 Th e report acknowledges that, In any event, human rights violations and abuses will oft en have both civil or political, and economic, social and cultural dimensions. […] Indeed, although wartime atrocities usually involve the “core” human rights, like the right to life and the protection against cruel and inhuman treatment, the confl ict in Sierra Leone may also have involved, and have been caused by, “violations of such economic and social rights as the right to food, to housing and to medical care”.111 In the resulting investigation, the Commission did investigate and report on aspects of economic and social rights such as education and health especially in relation to children112 and women. In a move to be commended it held a special hearing for women and girls. Th e Commission found that women bore the brunt of economic and social rights violations such as destruction of property, forced evictions and displacement,113 but the legal analysis never explicitly framed these abuses as human rights violations (right to housing, food and water for example). In terms of reparations, the programme was necessarily limited due to resources. Th e priority entitlement was defi ned not by the type of violations suff ered but by identifying the most vulnerable.114 As such, the Commission prioritised reparations for widows, children and in the areas of health, education, pensions and community reparations.115 Despite the fact that the reparations programme did address some issues which remedied economic and social rights violations116 these reparations were not recognised as remedies for violations of such rights and therefore were not framed as legal entitlements. Rather, these issues were addressed because they were deemed important policy issues and priorities for the identifi ed vulnerable groups. In sum, the above cases of Liberia and Sierra Leone illustrate that even if economic and social rights are explicitly provided for in the mandate and acknowledged as a causal factor of the confl ict, it does not necessarily follow that truth and reconciliation 110 Sierra Leone Truth and Reconciliation Commission, Witness to Truth – Report of the Sierra Leone Truth and Reconciliation Commission Vol. 1 (Sierra Leone Truth And Reconciliation Commission 2004) 38, para 54. 111 Ibid para 52. 112 See Sierra Leone Truth and Reconciliation Commission Witness to Truth – Report of the Sierra Leone Truth and Reconciliation Commission Vol. 2, Chapter 2 Findings (Sierra Leone Truth And Reconciliation Commission 2004) para 489; para 490. 113 Sierra Leone Truth and Reconciliation Commission, Witness to Truth – Report of the Sierra Leone Truth and Reconciliation Commission Vol.3B, Chapter Th ree Women and the Armed Confl ict in Sierra Leone (Sierra Leone Truth And Reconciliation Commission 2004) 185, para 386; See also Vol.2, Chapter 2 Findings: Women, para 497; para 499. 114 Sierra Leone Truth and Reconciliation Commission (n 112) para 57. 115 Ibid paras 84 and 85. 116 Such as lack of access to land; training and education; See Sierra Leone Truth and Reconciliation Commission (n 112) para 499; (n 113) 185 para 499. Foregrounding Socio-Economic Rights in Transitional Justice Netherlands Quarterly of Human Rights, Vol. 32/2 (2014) 205 commissions will apply a rights based framework to such violations or highlight them as a priority for the said commission. 4.2.4. Timor – Leste (East Timor) In the case of Th e Commission for Reception, Truth and Reconciliation in Timor- Leste, (CAVR) the commission also acknowledged and investigated violations of economic and social rights violations. Th e Commission’s mandate stated that they would enquire into ‘Violations of a broad range of human rights standards’ including rights and freedoms within, inter alia, the UN International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights 1966.117 Th e CAVR was also important in that it highlighted and recognised within its mandate the interdependence of rights.118 For example, a disappearance constitutes a violation not only of personal integrity rights (civil and political rights) but also where a family was economically dependent on the disappeared person may violate economic and social rights such as the right to an adequate standard of living.119 Th e Commission chose to focus on an examination of the most serious violations of fundamental rights and focused in particular on inter alia, ‘Th e range of rights relevant to displacement, resettlement and famine (the right to food, freedom from hunger, water and adequate housing, freedom of movement, freedom to choose a residence)’120 and ‘Social and economic rights’.121 Th e result was an in-depth report detailing extensive violations in relation to the rights to food, water, health, housing and education.122 Th e deliberate policy of forced displacement led to famine, ‘hunger and deprivation of the means of making a livelihood through the destruction of or 117 Th e Commission for Reception, Truth and Reconciliation in Timor-Leste, Chega! Th e Report of the Commission for Reception, Truth and Reconciliation in Timor-Leste (CAVR) (Commission for Reception, Truth and Reconciliation 31 October 2005) Part 2 – Th e Mandate of the Commission, 4, para 15. Other sources used include international human rights law but also international criminal law (such as crimes against humanity Art 7(2)(b) Rome Statute on extermination through deprivation of food) and international humanitarian law (for example, starvation as a weapon of war under grave breaches of the laws of war), as well as national law (for example, poisoning of water sources under Indonesian law). 118 As did the Sierra Leone Truth and Reconciliation Commission: See Sierra Leone Truth and Reconciliation Commission (n 110) 37–38. 119 Th e Commission for Reception, Truth and Reconciliation in Timor-Leste (n117) para 84, page 18. See also the Offi ce of the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights, Fact Sheet 6/Rev.3, Enforced or Involuntary Disappearances, Geneva: United Nations, July 2009, 3–4. 120 Th e Commission for Reception, Truth and Reconciliation in Timor-Leste (n 117) para 16 (3). 121 Ibid para 16 (11). See also paras 86–88, page19 and paras 128–132, pages 26–27. 122 Th e Commission for Reception, Truth and Reconciliation in Timor-Leste, Chega! Th e Report of the Commission for Reception, Truth and Reconciliation in Timor-Leste (CAVR), Section 7.3 Forced Displacement and Famine (Commission for Reception, Truth and Reconciliation 31 October 2005). See also CAVR, Forced Displacement and Famine, National Public Hearing, 28–29 July 2003, CAVR, 2005. Amanda Cahill-Ripley 206 Intersentia loss of access to food crops, livestock, housing, agricultural implements and land’.123 For others it resulted in death. In its detailed report on the fi ndings in relation to famine and displacement124 the Commission found that, Death was caused by famine, famine-related diseases, vulnerability to sickness from hunger, fear or exhaustion and a lack of access to medical care. It is likely that more people died from the eff ects of displacement than from any other violation, while the actual number of deaths is incalculable.125 Unfortunately, despite the severe, systematic and extensive nature of these socio-economic rights violations they were not remedied under the reparations programme. Rather, the CAVR felt it had pushed the scope of its mandate as far as was possible in the circumstances and stopped short of seeking remedy for these violations, due to the ‘principles of feasibility and prioritisation based on need’.126 Th e result was a reparations programme focused upon and limited to victims of torture, people with mental and physical disabilities and victims of sexual violence.127 However, the reparations programme also identifi ed recipients on the basis of vulnerability. Th erefore widows and children were targeted. Th is also meant that for some victims of economic and social rights violations reparations of some kind were given.128 Th e approach though was not one which prioritised victims of economic and social rights violations. Many people who had been made homeless, had suff ered starvation, malnutrition and a lack of education were excluded from the programme. What is signifi cant about the transitional justice process in this case was the explicit human rights framework applied to the economic and social rights violations. In this process these rights violations were framed as such and reference was made to international human rights law. Consequently, socio-economic rights violations were brought in some way to the foreground of transitional justice concerns, although ultimately they were not treated on an equal footing with violations of civil and political rights. Despite an explicit and specifi c mandate to investigate economic and social rights violations, priority was given in the end to reparations for civil and political rights violations. Of course there are many reasons why this might have been 123 Th e Commission for Reception, Truth and Reconciliation in Timor-Leste (n 122) Section 7.3.7, para 503(5). 124 Ibid. 125 Th e Commission for Reception, Truth and Reconciliation in Timor-Leste (n 122) para 503(4). 126 Th e Commission for Reception, Truth and Reconciliation in Timor-Leste, Chega! Th e Report of the Commission for Reception, Truth and Reconciliation in Timor-Leste (CAVR), Recommendations Part 11, 12.6 Guiding principles for a reparations programme in Timor-Leste (Commission for Reception, Truth and Reconciliation 31 October 2005) 39–41. 127 Ibid. 128 Reparations can take many forms. In this case for example, school fees were paid, access to rehabilitation and healthcare was given as well as skills training for women. See Th e Commission for Reception, Truth and Reconciliation in Timor-Leste (n 126) 12.12 Methods, pages 43–45. Foregrounding Socio-Economic Rights in Transitional Justice Netherlands Quarterly of Human Rights, Vol. 32/2 (2014) 207 the case, not least the capacity of the CAVR to act and enforce any reparations for such rights violations. However, as Sharp notes, this served to promote a ‘hierarchy of rights’ and granted de facto impunity to those responsible for ‘economic violence’.129 On a positive note though, the experiences of the CAVR represent a clear development in mandate of a truth and reconciliation process regarding investigation and reporting of fi ndings of economic and social rights violations. Overall, the evidence illustrates that truth and reconciliation commissions have the potential to address both direct grave violations of economic and social rights and more structural ongoing violations of these rights, if they are brought to the foreground of the mandate and crucially the focus remains throughout the process. Th ere is a need to build upon the past experiences to date. If we look at the experience of South Africa today it is evident that the legacy of structural injustice still exists. Racial and social divisions remain (although not legally sanctioned), for instance in healthcare, education and housing.130 Th is situation remains despite the enshrinement of economic and social rights in the South African Constitution and substantial jurisprudence concerning socio-economic rights within the constitutional court. An interesting and important question to ask is if violations of economic and social rights had been brought to the foreground of the SATRC, then would the outcome and the impact upon long-term peace and reconciliation in South Africa have been any diff erent? Th e experience of the CAVR in Timor-Leste is arguably a more positive development in terms of the recognition of economic and social rights violations as genuine crimes with legal standing which can be investigated and examined within the main body of work of a truth commission and with eff ective fi ndings. Th e CAVR process marks the beginning of foregrounding of such rights, even if not seen through to specifi c remedy or reparations. It signifi es a move away from economic and social rights violations as background or contextual information. As such, the work of the CAVR is to be commended and built upon for the future as an example of good practice. In addition, the specialised hearings of the SATRC and the Sierra Leone Truth and Reconciliation Commission are useful in drawing attention to the structural injustices and endemic economic and social rights violations within a regime. Both these methods (and a combination of the two) are markedly useful in documenting evidence of economic and social rights violations during confl ict and transition. 129 Sharp (n 17) 795. 130 Although black people are ‘free’ to access all services and goods that white people are, economically and socially black people remain marginalised. Race and class remain inextricably linked. See Wale. K, Confronting Exclusion: Time for Radical Reconciliation, SA Reconciliation Barometer Survey: 2013 Report (Institute for Justice and Reconciliation 2013) 7; Bertelsmann Stift ung, BTI 2014 – South Africa Country Report (Gütersloh: Bertelsmann Stift ung 2014) 14, 23. Amanda Cahill-Ripley 208 Intersentia 5. HOW TO MOVE FORWARD – DEVELOPING TRANSITIONAL JUSTICE AND ADDRESSING REMAINING CHALLENGES One of the most diffi cult challenges facing incorporation of economic and social rights within transitional justice mechanisms is how to design and implement a meaningful and eff ective reparations programme and the wider question of what should be considered remedy. Is the right to be heard remedy enough? As noted above reparations for violations of socio-economic rights have been lacking, even where transitional justice mechanisms have engaged with such violations as a part of their mandate. Th e question of reparations goes beyond the remit of this article. Suffi ce to say that further research is required in this area to explore the nature and form of reparations for economic and social rights violations, including the notion of community rather than individual reparations; non-fi nancial reparations and the relationship between community reparations and the right to development.131 A second and related challenge is which transitional justice mechanism to choose and how to delineate boundaries for the scope of the investigation into economic and social rights violations. Of course the choice of mechanism and scope of investigation will be partly subjective to each transition in question and the drivers of that particular confl ict, but these choices have implications for the consideration (or not) of such rights violations. Th e choice of mechanism could limit the extent to which economic and social rights violations are a part of the mandate. Th e choice of mechanism is also signifi cant in relation to the needs of the local population and grassroots demands for justice (and peace and reconciliation). Local communities oft en feel that international and legalistic transitional justice mechanisms result in their exclusion or marginalisation from the process.132 International eff orts are oft en led by the agenda of external actors rather than by local priorities for justice. An interesting example of local demands for transitional justice in relation to violations of economic and social rights can be seen in Colombia, where local communities have called for a reparations programme to specifi cally address economic and social rights 131 L. Magarrell, Reparations in Th eory and Practice, Reparative Justice Series (International Center for Transitional Justice 2007) at ; Lisa Laplante (n 29); C. Sandoval Villalba, for Redress, Rehabilitation As A Form Of Reparation Under International Law (Th e Redress Trust 2009); L. McGregor and C. Sandoval Villalba (eds) Th e Law and Practice of Reparations as a form of Rehabilitation (forthcoming 2014); Naomi Roht-Arriaza, Reparations and Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights (16 November 2012) available at SSRN: ; Th eo van Boven, Th e United Nations Basic Principles And Guidelines On Th e Right To A Remedy And Reparation For Victims Of Gross Violations Of International Human Rights Law And Serious Violations Of International Humanitarian Law (16 Dec 2005) (United Nations Audio Visual Library 2010) at (last accessed 17 June 2013). 132 McEvoy and McGregor (n 43). Foregrounding Socio-Economic Rights in Transitional Justice Netherlands Quarterly of Human Rights, Vol. 32/2 (2014) 209 violations including the right to social services and land restitution.133 One argument for the inclusion of economic and social rights within transitional justice is therefore, ‘where it refl ects the needs and priorities of victims’.134 When establishing the parameters for economic and social rights violations that will be considered as part of the transitional justice process, the question is how does one diff erentiate between violations that pre-dated the confl ict and those that are a consequence of the confl ict? As noted, it is questionable that this is even possible or desirable but certainly direct and deliberate grave violations of economic and social rights must be considered. Where possible, existing structural violence in the form of socio-economic violations should also be identifi ed and addressed, especially where these violations are root causes of confl ict. As Carranza notes ‘gains could be unmade if the conditions that led to or aggravated repression and confl ict are left to fester, allowing repression to re-emerge and confl ict to reoccur’.135 Another priority is to recognise the need for inclusion of economic and social rights in order to address violations suff ered by women during confl ict and transition. Th e lack of engagement with economic and social rights violations continues to have negative repercussions for the understanding of the abuses suff ered by women and girls during confl ict, as well as underestimating the prevalence of economic and social rights violations encountered during confl ict. To illustrate, the SATRC recognised and admitted that their limited defi nition of gross human rights violations ‘resulted in a blindness to the types of abuse predominantly experienced by women’.136 Commonly women and children are disproportionately aff ected by violations of socio-economic rights both in peacetime and confl ict and as such transitional justice mechanisms need to account for these rights violations if they are to suffi ciently address justice for women. Moreover, this neglect of the experiences of women and other vulnerable groups could result in the transitional justice process actually reasserting the subordination of disadvantaged groups that existed before and during the confl ict. Th e chosen mechanisms are at risk of echoing previously unjust distributions of economic and social rights, for example, where property and land is vested in men, and consolidating pre-existing inequalities ‘at personal, social and structural levels’.137 Where transitional justice procedures do make special provision for women, such as the special hearings in South Africa and Sierra Leone, the focus tends to be solely on sexual violence rather than on economic and social rights violations aff ecting 133 N. Summers, ‘Colombia’s Victims’ Law: Transitional Justice in a Time of Violent Confl ict?’ (2012) 25 Harvard Human Rights Journal 220; C. Diaz, ‘Challenging Impunity from Below: Th e Contested Ownership of Transitional Justice in Colombia’ in McEvoy and McGregor (n 43) 189–215. 134 Waldorf (n 1) 175. See also Carranza (n 18) 322. 135 Carranza (n 18) 329. 136 South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission (n 102) 318 and para 144. 137 E. Stanley, ‘Th e Political Economy of Transitional Justice in Timor-Leste’, in McEvoy and McGregor (n 40) 167–187, 185. Amanda Cahill-Ripley 210 Intersentia women. Hearing the accounts of all types of violations endured by women would result in a more truthful account of confl ict and reveal underlying gender dimensions of confl icts.138 Th erefore the inclusion of economic and social rights concerns within transitional justice mechanisms will also contribute to a more holistic and inclusive transitional justice process. Moreover, women are commonly aff ected by land issues during transitions. For example, they are oft en excluded from owning land under local custom, which impacts upon their ability to seek restitution following displacement.139 Transitional justice mechanisms have not adequately considered how to deal with violations related to land, such as displacement and destruction of property, resulting in violations of the rights to food, health, water, housing and work and in the worst cases loss of life.140 Th e issue of land sits at the intersection between economic and social rights, civil and political rights, international criminal law, international humanitarian law and local custom and domestic law. As such, further research, both theoretical and empirical, is required as to how best to address land issues in transition.141 As a further issue to explore, an examination and further discussion of how to address violations of economic and social rights both within transitional justice mechanisms but also in relation to wider peacebuilding is required. Th is will necessarily entail examining the broader idea of transitional justice. Where do the boundaries lie between transitional justice and peacebuilding?142 Certainly, transitional justice is oft en perceived as a pillar or component of peacebuilding and  post-confl ict reconciliation.143 What are the aims of transitional justice and should a shift from transitional justice to an inclusive process of transformative 138 Schmid (n 5) 6 and 16. Further reading on transitional justice and gender see S. Buckly-Zistel and R. Stanley, Gender in Transitional Justice (Palgrave Macmillan 2012); E. Zinsstag and M. Fineman (Eds), Feminist Perspectives on Transitional Justice: From International and Criminal to Alternative Forms of Justice (Series on Transitional Justice, Intersentia 2013); C. O’Rourke, Gender Politics in Transitional Justice (Routledge 2013). 139 L. Hovil, ‘Th e Nexus between Displacement and Transitional Justice: A Gender-Justice Dimension’ in R. Duthie (ed), Transitional Justice and Displacement (International Center for Transitional Justice/Social Science Research Council 2012) 329, 348. 140 As previously noted the Commission for Reception, Truth and Reconciliation in Timor-Leste, experience is a good starting point regarding land and displacement and ESR. 141 Recent articles which examine land and transitional justice include, M. Evans, ‘Land, socio- economic rights and transformative justice’ Paper presented at Land Divided: Land and South African Society in 2013, in Comparative Perspective conference, University of Cape Town, 24– 27 March 2013; O. Zenker, Land Restitution and Transitional Justice in Post-Apartheid South Africa, Max Planck Institute for Social Anthropology Working Paper No.134 (Max Planck Institute for Social Anthropology 2011). 142 Th ere is a question as to whether there is a way to distinguish between economic and social rights violations that should be considered as an element of transitional justice as opposed to being a concern for post-confl ict reconstruction. See T. Pasipanodya, ‘A Deeper Justice: Economic and Social Justice as Transitional Justice in Nepal’ (2008) 2 International Journal of Transitional Justice 378, 390. 143 Schmid (n 5) 8; Laplante (n 1) 347; van Zyl in Laplante (n 1) 333 note 11; Sharp (n 17) 781. Foregrounding Socio-Economic Rights in Transitional Justice Netherlands Quarterly of Human Rights, Vol. 32/2 (2014) 211 justice be considered? Whether transitional justice and peacebuilding is viewed as part of the same process or as parallel developments, it is clear that there is potential for impact stemming from the decisions of transitional justice bodies, in terms of remedy and reparations for violations of economic and social rights, upon the future realisation and enjoyment of these rights at both a legal and practical level. Experiences in Liberia, Nepal and Timor-Leste all support the thesis that transitional justice and peacebuilding need to be elements of an integral process. If a peace agreement and/or constitution incorporates economic and social rights144 then the transitional justice mechanisms that follow need to consider economic and social rights and the transitional justice body in turn can make recommendations that then seek to promote a framework for the realisation of these rights (both legal and structural). Without this continuity – if all the processes are seen as separate entities then gaps in eff ectiveness will continue. Of course, it does not necessarily follow that one step will follow from the next. For example, in the case of Nepal, despite adopting a peace agreement with a deep commitment to address economic and social rights145 there has been no explicit inclusion to date of these rights in the transitional justice mechanisms set up by the Nepalese government.146 Conversely, the recommendations of the Liberian Truth and Reconciliation Commission did call for reform of public institutions to promote good governance and human rights; to reduce poverty; to alleviate illiteracy and to provide equal access to public services.147 Although they did not address economic and social rights violations within a human rights framework, these recommendations should have a positive impact upon the enjoyment of these rights in the future. Th ese cases illustrate that the process needs to be looked at as a whole to ensure the optimal protection of economic and social rights. 6. CONCLUDING REMARKS Both prosecutorial justice and restorative justice mechanisms have failed to include economic and social rights as a core concern. As noted, this is in part due to the focus within transitional justice on criminal justice, the historical discourse on the nature of economic and social rights themselves and the non-justiciability arguments regarding them. It is evident that there is a need to redefi ne ideas of 144 Th e OHCHR note that ‘Constitutions and peace agreements off er further entry points for enshrining protections for economic, social and cultural rights in post-confl ict societies’ (OHCHR (n 1) para 63). 145 See the Comprehensive Peace Agreement concluded between the Government of Nepal and the Communist Party of Nepal (Maoist), November 21, 2006, sections 7.1.2 and 7.5 Economic and Social Rights including the right to food, health, education, social security. See also Th e Interim Constitution of Nepal, 2063 (2007). 146 Pasipanodya (n 142) 392; Schmid (n 5) 12. 147 Republic Of Liberia Truth And Reconciliation Commission (n 105) 11–12. Amanda Cahill-Ripley 212 Intersentia transitional justice to include a broader conception of justice, which includes both criminal justice and wider social justice. Th e inclusion of economic and social rights resulting in a more holistic process should make transitional justice mechanisms more eff ective to the needs of the people. ‘Demands for truth’ must also include the truth regarding past and existing violations of socio-economic rights. Evidently by bringing such rights violations to the foreground of a truth and reconciliation commission process rather than relegating economic and social rights violations to contextual or background information results in a more ‘truthful’ account of the confl ict and therefore more eff ective justice, truth and reconciliation. Moreover, transitional justice bodies need to hold those responsible for violations of economic and social rights to account just as it does for violations of civil and political rights. Th is will include seeking remedy for direct and deliberate acts of violence which violate economic and social rights but also seeking remedy where appropriate for more structural endemic violations which are a result of the ongoing confl ict and/or those that act as confl ict triggers.148 Furthermore, as Schmid notes ‘incorporating economic and social rights violations makes the rhetoric of the indivisibility and interdependence of rights a reality’.149 Th e following proposals formulate a minimum starting point for the development of a transitional justice process which addresses economic and social rights violations. In the fi rst instance, the body appointed to deal with transitional justice in a particular State should include members with expertise in the area of economic and social rights. Th is will improve their capacity to deal with violations of such rights. Furthermore, truth and reconciliation commissions and international courts and tribunals should include within their mandate a defi nition of human rights violations which includes socio-economic rights. Th eir mandate should include a capacity to investigate, examine and remedy these violations, including reparations (of some kind). As noted above, the issue of reparations for economic and social rights violations represents a challenge that requires further research. Moreover, if a State has not ratifi ed international treaties regarding economic and social rights150 the transitional justice body should recommend that they do so. Furthermore, the bodies should also consider recommendations for wider peacebuilding measures that could assist in the remedy and further protection of economic and social rights, both normative legal measures and practical measures for implementation of such rights. Finally, those involved in transitional justice both practice based and academic researchers should seek to 148 P. Gready, Th e Era of Transitional Justice – Th e Aft ermath of the Truth and Reconciliation Commission in South Africa and Beyond (Routledge GlassHouse 2011) 215. 149 Schmid (n 5) 19. 150 Inter alia, UN International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (n 53) and Optional Protocol to the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (adopted 10  December 2008, entered into force 5  May 2013) A/63/435; C.N.869.2009.TREATIES-34 of 11 December 2009. Foregrounding Socio-Economic Rights in Transitional Justice Netherlands Quarterly of Human Rights, Vol. 32/2 (2014) 213 gather evidence of best practice and to undertake further research on all aspects of economic and social rights, transitional justice and wider peacebuilding.151 If violations of economic and social rights continue to be omitted from or pushed to the background of transitional justice mechanisms, transitional justice cannot and will not be truly eff ective. Progress can be made if those working in the fi eld begin by accepting the premise that if the aim of transitional justice is to achieve justice for human rights violations as an element of sustainable peace, there is a need to address grave and deliberate violations of both economic and social rights and civil and political rights.152 Th ere is also a need to address where possible violations of economic and social rights which are systematic and structural.153 As a starting point it is evident that for transitional justice to be eff ective it needs to take into account any violations of economic and social rights that are prevalent during the time period established by the transitional justice mechanism as within their mandate. Moreover, it is important to note that the wider process of peacebuilding will also need to address these structural violations if peace is to be achieved. Human rights cannot make people trust one another or even like one another – this is the process of reconciliation. However, human rights can set minimum standards of humanity to follow in societies that are in transition from confl ict and repression to peace – protections to ensure people feel secure and safe and to allow them that security to start the process of reconciliation. Holding to account those who are responsible for grave violations of economic and social rights and realising these rights as a part of transitional justice and wider peacebuilding are therefore essential to any eff ective reconciliation process. Transitional justice should be concerned with aiding transition from violence to peace not solely through criminal justice but also through realisation of substantive social justice. Ultimately, there is a need to foreground violations of economic and social rights within transitional justice. Only then can it be truly eff ective. 151 For example further comparative analysis could be undertaken looking at the practice of truth commissions with regards to economic and social rights. Likewise, further research on the links between economic and social rights, transitional justice and peacebuilding is required. 152 Sharp (n 17) notes that this will include consideration and reorientation of the ‘transition’ in transitional justice from a narrow concern with transition to democracy to a broader concern with transition to positive peace and freedom from structural violence. 153 See UN Human Rights Council, Report of the Special Rapporteur on the promotion of truth, justice, reparation and guarantees of non-recurrence, Pablo de Greiff (9 August 2012) A/HRC/21/46 paras 50–51. work_56qftchbkjgdhe3lvvlgw46qgq ---- Cosmopolitism, Global Justice and International Law — Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam Skip to main navigation Skip to search Skip to main content Help & FAQ Home Profiles Research Units Research output Datasets Activities Prizes Press / Media Search by expertise, name or affiliation Cosmopolitism, Global Justice and International Law R. Pierik, W.G. Werner Transnational Legal Studies Boundaries of Law Research output: Contribution to Journal › Article › Academic 162 Downloads (Pure) Overview Original language English Pages (from-to) 679-684 Number of pages 6 Journal Leiden Journal of International law Volume 14 Issue number 4 DOIs https://doi.org/10.1017/s0922156505002955 Publication status Published - 2005 Access to Document 10.1017/s0922156505002955 184901Final published version, 57.6 KB Cite this APA Author BIBTEX Harvard Standard RIS Vancouver Pierik, R., & Werner, W. G. (2005). Cosmopolitism, Global Justice and International Law. Leiden Journal of International law, 14(4), 679-684. https://doi.org/10.1017/s0922156505002955 Pierik, R. ; Werner, W.G. / Cosmopolitism, Global Justice and International Law. In: Leiden Journal of International law. 2005 ; Vol. 14, No. 4. pp. 679-684. @article{740b15e7ac884c30a7cb3722975b4e84, title = "Cosmopolitism, Global Justice and International Law", author = "R. Pierik and W.G. Werner", year = "2005", doi = "10.1017/s0922156505002955", language = "English", volume = "14", pages = "679--684", journal = "Leiden Journal of International law", issn = "0922-1565", publisher = "Cambridge University Press", number = "4", } Pierik, R & Werner, WG 2005, 'Cosmopolitism, Global Justice and International Law', Leiden Journal of International law, vol. 14, no. 4, pp. 679-684. https://doi.org/10.1017/s0922156505002955 Cosmopolitism, Global Justice and International Law. / Pierik, R.; Werner, W.G. In: Leiden Journal of International law, Vol. 14, No. 4, 2005, p. 679-684.Research output: Contribution to Journal › Article › Academic TY - JOUR T1 - Cosmopolitism, Global Justice and International Law AU - Pierik, R. AU - Werner, W.G. PY - 2005 Y1 - 2005 U2 - 10.1017/s0922156505002955 DO - 10.1017/s0922156505002955 M3 - Article VL - 14 SP - 679 EP - 684 JO - Leiden Journal of International law JF - Leiden Journal of International law SN - 0922-1565 IS - 4 ER - Pierik R, Werner WG. Cosmopolitism, Global Justice and International Law. Leiden Journal of International law. 2005;14(4):679-684. https://doi.org/10.1017/s0922156505002955 Powered by Pure, Scopus & Elsevier Fingerprint Engine™ © 2021 Elsevier B.V. We use cookies to help provide and enhance our service and tailor content. By continuing you agree to the use of cookies Log in to Pure Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam data protection policy About web accessibility work_5aoaeza53faixdcvpbq4rjzjgu ---- Ageing, Justice, and Resource Allocation Walker, T. (2016). Ageing, Justice, and Resource Allocation. Journal of Medical Ethics, 42(6), 348-352. https://doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2016-103563 Published in: Journal of Medical Ethics Document Version: Peer reviewed version Queen's University Belfast - Research Portal: Link to publication record in Queen's University Belfast Research Portal Publisher rights Copyright 2016 the author. General rights Copyright for the publications made accessible via the Queen's University Belfast Research Portal is retained by the author(s) and / or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing these publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Take down policy The Research Portal is Queen's institutional repository that provides access to Queen's research output. Every effort has been made to ensure that content in the Research Portal does not infringe any person's rights, or applicable UK laws. If you discover content in the Research Portal that you believe breaches copyright or violates any law, please contact openaccess@qub.ac.uk. Download date:06. Apr. 2021 https://doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2016-103563 https://pure.qub.ac.uk/en/publications/ageing-justice-and-resource-allocation(71ce2e93-011a-477e-a76b-cf54e61c34b6).html 1 Ageing, justice, and resource allocation Abstract Around the world the population is ageing in ways that pose new challenges for health care providers. To date these have mostly been formulated in terms of challenges created by increasing costs, and the focus has been squarely on life prolonging treatments. However, this focus ignores the ways in which many older people require life enhancing treatments to counteract the effects of physical and mental decline. This paper argues that in doing so it misses important aspects of what justice requires when it comes to older people. Introduction In countries across the world an ever larger proportion of the population is living into old age (however we fix the limits of that).[1] The trajectory of an individual’s life in old age varies considerably from person to person.[1, 2] Some people die suddenly after living into old age with very few health problems. Others experience what in the past would have been life shortening illnesses but which can now be treated, even if they nevertheless recur. This can lead to a pattern of treatment and recovery where the recovery nevertheless leaves the patient with a lower level of health than earlier. Another pattern, one that becomes more prevalent as the population ages, is of gradual decline in physical functioning. The individual experiences one or several conditions that whilst not necessarily life threatening require medical treatment or assistance if they are not to adversely affect the quality of life. For these people, as Atul Gawande puts it the end comes as a result of “the accumulating crumbling of one’s bodily 2 systems while medicine carries out its maintenance measures and patch jobs. We reduce the blood pressure here, beat back the osteoarthritis there, control this disease, track that one, replace a failed joint, valve, piston, watch the central processing unit gradually give out. The curve of life becomes a long, slow fade”.[3] One consequence of these patterns of ageing is that as people age, and in particular as they live into old age, they become more likely to develop a range of conditions that cannot be cured but can be managed in a way that helps restore (or at least helps to slow the decline in) functioning – which in turn affects their ability to live their lives in the way they chose. These underlying conditions also mean that some things that can happen at any age (for example, catching influenza, or falling) pose a greater risk of serious harm or death to older people than to those who are younger. In this paper I will argue that these consequences of the different ways in which people age should be taken into account when assessing how to allocate healthcare resources. That is, I will argue that both how people age and the ways in which the chances of becoming ill or suffering severe harm vary with age are relevant for resource allocations decisions if older people are to be treated fairly. Because much of the existing debate on age and resource allocation does not adequately take account of these features, that debate is missing something important. In developing this argument I will be making three assumptions about the context in which these resource allocation decisions are being made. First, the decisions are being made within a healthcare system that provides treatments to people of all ages. Systems of this type are frequently Government funded but they need not be. Second, the resources available to those operating 3 the system are, and will remain, limited. Because of this not every treatment that would benefit patients can be provided. Third, fairness is a key consideration in determining what treatments to fund. In saying this, however, I do not mean to imply that it is necessarily the only consideration. As such, actual resource allocation decisions in practice may need to take into account much more than is considered in this paper. Resource allocation and an ageing population Ageing (and in particular living into very old age) increases the chances of developing a range of conditions (such as deteriorating hearing, osteoporosis, and type 2 diabetes) that cannot be cured but can be managed. To some extent these changes are inevitable. As the World Health Organization put it, “As people age, they experience a gradual accumulation of molecular and cellular damage that results in general decrease in physiological reserves. These broad physiological and homeostatic changes are largely inevitable, although their extent will vary significantly among individuals at any particular chronological age. On top of these underlying changes, exposures to a range of positive and negative environmental influences across the life course can influence the development of other health characteristics, such as physiological risk factors (for example, high blood pressure), diseases, injuries and broader geriatric syndromes.” [4] These conditions are not always life threatening if untreated, but can have significant negative impacts on a person’s quality of life unless interventions take place. These interventions may not tackle or reverse the underlying problem – just as glasses do not reverse the physiological changes that lead to deteriorating eyesight – but nevertheless help to maintain 4 functioning.[1,5] It is worth noting that these negative impacts are not necessarily caused simply by problems with the body. If I fall a few times I may be reluctant to go out on my own in case I fall (my confidence having been undermined). If I have bladder problems I may also be less willing to go out if public conveniences are not readily available. In these cases the physical problems I have developed are not the sole cause of the limitations in my life; those limitations are also affected by the social context. As society ages more and more people will develop these kinds of restrictions, but to date the implications of this for resource allocation decisions have not been extensively explored in the medical ethics literature – something that perhaps not surprising given the focus in medical ethics on acute care.[5] This is not to say that there has been no debate about the impacts of ageing on resource allocation. Such debates typically draw on figures showing that on average more is spent per person on older people (over 65) than on younger adults, and that even more per head is spent on what have come to be referred to as the old old (those over 75 or 80).[6,7] As the population ages it is then argued that there will be increasing pressure on health services. One response to this has been to investigate whether age should be used as a factor in prioritizing health care. A variety of arguments – the fair-innings argument [8,9], Daniels’ prudential lifespan argument [10,11,12], and Callahan’s communitarian argument [13,14] – have been put forward to argue that (at least in some cases) the old should have a lower priority for health care. In contrast John Harris has over a number of years stressed that for each person who wants to go on living the ‘rest of our lives’ is something that we value equally – irrespective of how old 5 we are or how long we may have left to live.[9, 15, 16] This leads to what he refers to as an ‘anti-ageist’ argument opposing deprioritizing treatments on the basis of age or expected life expectancy; an argument that denies absolutely the relevance of age as a criterion for whether someone should receive life prolonging treatment. An important feature of all these arguments is that they have only been concerned with treatments that extend life. Given their focus on the value of additional years or a normal lifespan, these arguments are not for the most part well suited to addressing resource allocation problems when it comes to the types of life enhancing treatments that are needed in response to physical or mental decline. Even if we agree, following Harris, that age should not be a criterion for the allocation of life prolonging treatments [9,15,16], and following Simona Giordano that age should not be criterion for the allocation of life enhancing treatments [17], this does not resolve the issue. We still need to determine how to allocate resources between these two where we cannot do both, and because the latter disproportionately affects older people this should be done in a way that does not discriminate unfairly against them. One option here, that is in line with Harris’ own account, is that life prolonging treatments should always have priority over life enhancing treatments (with the exception of treatments for conditions that would otherwise be completely debilitating).[15] In this context, however, this can lead to very counter intuitive results in practice. It would require that we not provide any life enhancing treatments for older people until after we had made sure that all life prolonging treatments that might be needed are available to those who need them – a point that might not in practice be reached (particularly in poorer 6 countries). Whilst Harris also argues that more resources should be allocated to healthcare, and this might seem to provide a way to respond to this point, his argument for increased spending is based on the priority he gives to protecting against threats to life and liberty [15,16] and as such would not extend to cover cases where resources may be needed to enhance quality of life but life is not itself under threat. The problem with such an approach is that it puts all the weight on prolonging life, and none at all on the quality of life. Effectively such an approach treats quality of life as unimportant, at least compared to length of life, when it comes to resource allocation decisions. If we only consider life prolonging treatment then this may not appear to be too much of a problem – it allows Harris to argue (as he does in the case of QALYs) that approaches that would give those whose quality of life is poor lower priority when it comes to life prolonging treatments fail to show everyone equal respect.[9,15,16] But when we turn our attention to the different ways in which health can be affected by ageing such an approach looks problematic. It threatens to leave older people to struggle on with increasing health problems, problems that could be alleviated should we choose to do so, because those problems are not themselves life threatening. Furthermore, people, including older people, are in their own lives willing to take risks with their future lives in order to do the things that are important to them and enhance the quality of their lives.[18,19] Both quality and quantity of life matter to us throughout our lives. A system that prioritises life prolonging treatment in the way just described fails to capture what is important in the lives 7 of the population. This is not an abstract theoretical point as at least to some extent current health care systems priortise in this way – that is, they focus their resources on acute care and curing those things that can be cured.[1,20,21] But as Atul Gawande puts it, “our most cruel failure in how we treat the sick and aged is the failure to recognize that they have priorities beyond merely being safe and living longer”.[22] A system that prioritises living longer above everything else will not reflect what is important to the lives of those the system is there to help. If we want a system that combines consideration of both life-enhancing and life- prolonging considerations, there are two options that have been widely discussed in medical ethics. The first adopts a cost- effectiveness approach that incorporates a measure of both the impact of a treatment on the length of life and its impact on the quality of that life. The most widely discussed option of this type is the quality adjusted life year (QALY).[23] There are however some practical problems in utilizing QALYs in this context. First, the effect of a particular intervention, as already noted, is dependent in part on factors other than the intervention itself – including the social context.[1] As the World Health Organization point out the environment can be a stronger influence on functioning than the underlying physiological changes because “it determines whether at any given level of intrinsic capacity we can ultimately do the things that are important to us.”[24] If that context is one in which older people are viewed as a problem, or as inevitably in decline and unable to do things, medical interventions may not be able to produce as beneficial an effect as they otherwise would. That is, in an ageist society interventions to improve the quality of life of older people by mitigating the impact of physical changes may 8 have compromised effectiveness. However, it would be morally problematic to conclude on that basis that they are not cost effective because the cost of the intervention does not produce as many additional quality adjusted life years as interventions aimed at other sections of the population. To do so would be to hit older people with a double blow – treatments that might improve their condition are not cost effective because they are already living in an unsupportive or discriminatory environment. Second, it is not unusual for older people to have more than one health problem and the solutions to those problems may be multifactorial.[25] Because of this working out the improvement in quality of life for any one intervention can be difficult – a problem that can be exacerbated when some interventions (for example, those that involve people providing care) can be a response to more than one problem. Third, if medical assistance is not provided this does not mean that the older person does not need help – those things that treatment would have enabled her to do may no longer be things that she can do, but these may still be things that have to be done (for example, washing herself, or buying food). Someone has to provide this assistance. That help may not be provided by the healthcare system but it will impact on the question of how much of an improvement in quality of life a medical intervention provides. This effectively can push support out of the healthcare system and onto families and friends. In turn, this raises significant issues about the extent to which it is appropriate to rely on such a system, particularly given its disproportionate effect on women (who fill most of the caring roles). Giving wider social changes this may not be either fair or sustainable.[1] A focus just on the effects of a particular intervention can miss all these wider social questions, and can operate on the assumption that they will continue as before. But that 9 does not necessarily help to ensure that justice is provided for older people in the provision of healthcare resources. An alternative to QALYs is to adopt a whole life course approach along the lines argued for by Norman Daniels.[10,11,12] Daniels argues that age is different from other features such as ethnic group or sex because most of us (if we are fortunate) will pass through different ages – those who are now old were young once, and many of those young now will become old. As such, decisions about spending on health care at different stages of life can be thought of, not in terms of which person will get the treatment or intervention, but in terms of what would be available to each person at different stages of his or her life. Because we are prone to view things from the stage of life we are currently at, Daniels adopts a position that requires that we make a decision independent of that knowledge. In doing so he asks us to consider (in a context in which choices have to be made because not all health care that is needed or wanted can in fact be provided) what we would use our resources to insure against, and how that insurance cover would be linked to the different parts of our lives. Whilst in earlier work this approach was used to argue in favour of prioritizing life prolonging treatments for the young over the old – on the basis that a prudent and rational person would put more into ensuring they live to be old than that they continue to live once they are already old – Daniels more recently has argued that this will only be the case in unusual circumstances.[12] In utilizing such an approach to address the problems we are concerned with in this paper it will be useful to start with a criticism of systems, like QALYs, that 10 value both quality and quantity of life. That we do not always prioritise living longer over everything else in our own lives does not mean, as Harris argues in his criticism of QALYs, that we will necessarily agree to a system that denies us life prolonging treatment to improve someone else’s quality of life (even where we would make that trade off in our own life).[9] But this need not be surprising – I will prefer the option that benefits me, or those close to me, where I have a choice simply because this matters more to me. An approach like that of Norman Daniels’ outlined above is designed to avoid this personal bias. When we think about what we would insure against in a situation where we cannot insure against everything (and do not know what ill health we will experience) it is unlikely that we would choose to ensure that we would have access to life prolonging treatment whenever it is needed and only after that has been done buy insurance that provides cover for chronic conditions or treatments that will mitigate (and help compensate for loss of functioning caused by) things like diabetes, osteoporosis, worn out joints, and loss of hearing or vision. Instead we would try to ensure that there will be support for us if we develop these kinds of condition.[12] If that is what we would each choose then none of us has reasonable grounds to complain if the allocation of healthcare resources reflects this – and note that this applies even if the resulting allocation means that life prolonging treatment is not available when we need it (we were willing to take the chance that it was not available in order to ensure other things were). If this is right then what are the implications for questions of justice when it comes to an ageing population? There are two that are important in the context of this paper. First, as a population ages the proportion of its healthcare 11 resources that go to treatments that enhance the lives of older people should rise faster than the rate of increase of the proportion of older people in the population. If very few people live beyond 65 then the chances of any one of us needing treatment for things like osteoporosis or dementia are low (the chances of us developing these conditions goes up with age and goes up at an increasing rate once we pass 65). Given the low likelihood of needing such treatment it may be rational not to put many resources into ensuring treatment is available should we develop these conditions. Other things that pose more of a risk to our health, including things that pose a risk to our living into old age, may reasonably have higher priority. It may be reasonable to prioritise life prolonging treatments that will help ensure we live into old age, rather than treatments that would enhance the quality of our lives should we develop particular chronic conditions in old age. But as life expectancy goes up things change. As the chance that a person will live beyond 65 increases the chance of them developing the kinds of condition that are the focus of this paper also increases. Furthermore it does so in a way that should make a difference in how we allocate health care resources. If the chances of developing a chronic illness were the same whatever our age then as we live longer the chances of developing it at some point in our lifetime go up (there is a chance that we develop the condition in any one year and so the chances that we develop it in the course of a lifetime goes up the longer we live). If this was the case for all conditions then living longer need not alter the relative distribution of resources between conditions – they all equally become more likely over the course of our lifetime. But this is not the case as we have seen with all conditions. For those conditions that are our focus here the chances of 12 developing them as we live longer goes up not only in absolute terms but also relative to other types of condition. Given this shift a rational and prudent person would change their priorities when thinking about what to insure against. They would give higher priority than before to providing resources to help with the conditions that are more likely to occur in old age. What this means is that as the population ages resources for providing support for the chronic and potentially limiting conditions that are more common among those who are older should take up a larger proportion of those available. What would have been fair and appropriate when life expectancy was lower will no longer be so. Making such shifts in practice runs into institutional inertia and so can be difficult. But a failure to do so leads to a mismatch between the services provided and what justice requires. Those who lose out in this mismatch are those who are older – they are the ones who are treated unfairly by a failure to change. We might argue that in this way a failure to change results in a system that does not provide equal consideration to those who are older adults. It is worth noting in this context that the World Health Organization have reported that around the world “there is low priority within health policy to the challenge of the demographic transition” of ageing populations.[26] On the account developed here justice requires that this change. Second, what fairness requires when it comes to the allocation of healthcare resources – in particular what it requires when it comes to the balance to be struck between life prolonging and life enhancing treatments – cannot be determined by focusing purely on the ways different treatments affect patients’ health. As we have just seen life expectancy affects how this balance should be 13 made. Furthermore, as described earlier, features of the wider social environment are also relevant. For this reason assessments of what fairness requires when it comes to resource allocation need to be rooted in details of the population that is served by the healthcare system. In turn this means that what will count as a fair distribution of healthcare resources will vary depending on the context. A way of splitting resources between life prolonging and life enhancing treatments may be fair when it comes to a particular population, but this does not mean that it would be fair for a different population or even for that same population at a later time. This consequence of taking into account the ways people age places significant limits on what can be said in abstract terms about what a fair healthcare resource allocation system would look like. Adopting Daniels’ prudential lifespan approach does, however, give some guidance about how to go about making an assessment of whether a particular allocation would be fair in any given context. As has already been pointed out this approach requires that decision makers consider what rational and informed individuals would use the limited resources available to insure against, and how that insurance cover would be linked to the different parts of their lives. However, as Daniels has himself argued, there may well be reasonable disagreement among such decision makers, all of whom are well informed, about where to draw the line between different types of treatment, and more broadly between provision of treatment that is life prolonging and that which is life enhancing.[12] As a result, what is needed when making decisions about the distribution of healthcare resources within a healthcare system that serves a particular population is both a means to bring 14 together these different perspectives and a fair procedure for resolving the resulting disagreements. Arguing for, and defending, any such procedures would take us beyond the aims of (and space available in) this paper. My aim has not been to argue that a particular way of distributing resources is fair or unfair. It has instead been to argue that certain types of information – about patterns of ageing, about average life expectancy, about the ways in which the chances of developing certain conditions changes with age – are relevant when it comes to assessing the fairness of resource allocation arrangements, and that these types of information have not been given adequate weight in accounts of the connections between age and resource allocation in healthcare. The relevance of age in some contexts As we have already seen an anti-ageist argument in debates about resource allocation takes it that age should not be a criterion when determining what treatments to give (at least in the case of life prolonging treatments). To use age in this way would, it is argued, fail to show equal consideration and respect for people who are older – that is it would violate what Harris calls the ‘age indifference principle’.[16,17] In this section I want to argue that whatever its merits when it comes to life prolonging treatments (something I will not address here), when it comes to preventative measures this approach is flawed. That is, I will argue that (at least in some cases) allocating interventions using age as a criterion is both wholly consistent with showing equal consideration to older people, and morally required. 15 In order to develop this argument it will be useful to start with an example. In the UK those over 65 are routinely offered vaccinations against influenza, something that is not offered to adults under 65 unless they fall into one of several fairly narrowly defined ‘high risk’ categories.[27] Similarly, in the UK the National Institute for Health and Care Excellence guidelines on falls require doctors to ask patients over 65 about falls in the past year, but they are not required to do this for younger patients (with the exception of patients over 55 who fulfill other set criteria).[28] A potential problem for these kinds of age based policies is that whilst risk (or increased risk) is associated with age, it is not the case that merely being older means that as an individual one has a higher risk of serious harm than all those one is older than. That is, the policies offer steps to prevent serious harm due to infection or falls to some individuals whilst denying it to others, even where at the individual level the latter may be as likely to experience those harms as the former. We might conclude from this that age should not be a factor in determining which interventions to provide – the interventions should be available to all, to none, or only to those who are in fact at higher risk. The problem with this response, however, is that each of these options faces significant challenges. Offering influenza vaccine to all adults, for example, would considerably increase the cost of the vaccination program in a way that does not produce anything like comparable increases in benefit. This may in turn lead to a judgment that vaccination is not cost effective when compared to other kinds of preventative medicine that could be introduced, and thus to this not being a viable option. Not offering the vaccine to anyone however would be to leave a large group, older 16 adults, at risk of serious harm – harm that could have been prevented. This would be the case because they, as a group, are more likely to experience this harm than those who are younger than them. Because the risk is not consistent across the life course, but increases with age, they will lose out. This does not appear to be consistent with fair treatment of older people. It might be thought that this can be avoided by only giving the vaccination to those who are in fact at higher risk – this will include some but not all older people. However, this response assumes that we can draw a line to distinguish what characterizes those at increased risk in a way that is independent of age. This may not in practice be possible when drawing up policy – or at least may not be possible without spending more than the costs of offering the intervention to all above a certain age. The patterns of ageing that can lead to increased risk are of many different types, and it is not clear that there is a way of characterizing them that picks up all those at increased risk of serious harm. That is, there is not necessarily a way of picking out all and only those at increased risk. In that case any policy will draw the line between those who are included and those who are excluded from provision of some intervention in a way that either excludes some at higher risk, or includes some at lower risk. The question is really about how we should go about doing this. A way to address this problem is, as above, to make use of Daniels’ prudential lifespan approach.[10,11,12] The advantage of this approach for our purposes here is that it asks us to consider the ways in which we would want resources to be available across our own lives and excludes knowledge of our own health 17 status. In that context it would appear reasonable to choose to have protection and preventative measures available when the risks are high. If we were to use our resources to provide vaccination against influenza to all adults we will be using resources in a way that provides little expected benefit. In contrast, given the increased risks when older and the knowledge that we are likely to live to those older ages, ensuring that the vaccine is available then would provide greater potential benefits. There may be reasonable differences about what exactly we would agree to in determining what preventative measures would be available at what points in our life (this will in part depend on what else we need to take account of). But for our purposes here we can put this to one side. The point I want to draw out is that using this approach highlights the relevance for healthcare allocation decisions of the ways in which risk varies across the life course. Because the risks are higher when older this means that we should prioritise protection, and preventative measures, for those who are older (along with other high risk groups). In the case of influenza vaccination this would mean we should prioritise vaccinations for those who are older over those who are younger. This does not stem from giving the lives of younger adults lower priority. Instead it stems from the fact that age is associated with increased risk of serious harm. Concluding remarks When it comes to resource allocation decisions I have argued that the increasing chances of becoming ill or losing function as we age matter. The account given may be challenged in its details. But my aim has not been simply to argue for that account, it has been to argue that the focus on age in resource allocation 18 decisions has shone a bright light on some areas, but left others (which are also important) in the dark. The arguments above aim to throw some light on them and are in part a plea for more work in this area. However, before finishing it is important to point out that when we shift from questions about resource allocation to consider interventions with particular patients the focus on a process of decline as one of the patterns of ageing brings with it risks and challenges of its own. This is because when we focus at the group level we are concerned with probabilities, but as highlighted at the start of this paper these group characteristics cover a wide range of different patterns of ageing. A failure to remember that different people age in different ways, and that there are many trajectories that a person can traverse as they age, can at the individual level lead to problematic outcomes (particularly in a culture that is steeped in narratives of ageing as decline). One potential danger here is that healthcare professionals may jump too quickly when an older patient shows signs of confusion (or simply comes to what looks to be a poor decision) to an assessment that he or she lacks capacity.[29] Having said this, the right response to this possibility is not to ignore the increased risks that come with growing older. To do that is to risk failing to provide appropriate care and support where it is in fact needed. We do not, or should not, want doctors and other healthcare professionals to ignore indications of underlying health problems (either physical or psychological). However, it is important that they bear in mind that these are only indicators that something may be wrong, not that something is wrong. This is a potentially tricky balancing act to get right, particularly in a culture in which stereotypes of older people are prevalent. It requires judgment 19 and skill on behalf of the attending healthcare professional because there are two ways in which a healthcare professional can go wrong in this context – failing to recognize and respect the older patient’s autonomy because too much was read into features their behavior or choices, or failing to recognize underlying health problems and hence failing to address them. Either way risks acting in a way that is inconsistent with principles of medical ethics. References 1 World Health Organization. World report on ageing and health. 2015. http://apps.who.int/iris/bitstream/10665/186463/1/978924094811_eng.pdf? ua=1 (accessed December 2015) 2 Lunney J.R., Lynn J., Foley D.J. et al. Patterns of functional decline at the end of life. The Journal of the American Medical Association 2003;289(18):2387-2392 3 Gawande A. Being Mortal: Illness, Medicine and What Matters in the End. London: Profile Books Ltd 2014: 28 4 World Health Organization. World report on ageing and health. 2015. http://apps.who.int/iris/bitstream/10665/186463/1/978924094811_eng.pdf? ua=1 (accessed December 2015) at p.29 5 Silvers A. Judgment and justice: Evaluating health care for chronically ill and disabled patients. In Rhodes R, Francis LP, Silvers A, eds. The Blackwell Guide to Medical Ethics. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2007:354-372 http://apps.who.int/iris/bitstream/10665/186463/1/978924094811_eng.pdf?ua=1 http://apps.who.int/iris/bitstream/10665/186463/1/978924094811_eng.pdf?ua=1 http://apps.who.int/iris/bitstream/10665/186463/1/978924094811_eng.pdf?ua=1 http://apps.who.int/iris/bitstream/10665/186463/1/978924094811_eng.pdf?ua=1 20 6 Wanless D. Securing Good Care for Older People: Taking a Long-Term View. London: King’s Fund 2006 7 Casey B, Oxley H, Whitehouse E, et al. Policies for an Ageing Society: Recent Measures and Areas for Further Reform. Paris: OECD 2003 8 Williams A. Intergenerational equity: An exploration of the ‘fair-innings’ argument’. Health Economics 1997;6:117-132 9 Harris J. The Value of Life. Abingdon: Routledge and Kegan Paul 1985: 91-102 10 Daniels N. Am I My Parents’ Keeper. Oxford: Oxford University Press 1988 11 Daniels N. Justice between generations. Journal of Political Theory 2008;16(4):475-494 12 Daniels N. Just Health: Meeting Health Needs Fairly. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2008: 161-190 13 Callahan D. Old age and new policy. Journal of the American Medical Association 1989;261(6):905-906 14 Callahan D. Setting Limits, What Kind of Life. New York: Simon and Schuster 1990 21 15 Harris J. QALYfying the value of life. Journal of Medical Ethics 1987;13:117- 123 16 Harris J. The age-indifference principle and equality. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2005;14:93-99 17 Giordano S. Respect for equality and the treatment of the elderly: Declarations of human rights and age-based rationing. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2005;14:83-92 18 Bowling A, Dieppe P. What is successful ageing and who should define it? BMJ 2005;331(7531):1548-1551 19 Grewal I, Lewis J, Flynn T, et al. Developing attributes for a generic quality of life measure for older people: preferences and capabilities. Social Science and Medicine 2006;62(8):1891-1901 20 Goodwin N, Sonola L, Theil v, et al. Co-ordinated Care for People with Chronic Complex Conditions: Key Lessons and Markers for Success. London: The King’s Fund 2013 21 Smith SM, Soubhi H, Fortin M, et al. Managing patients with multimorbidity: systematic review of interventions in primary care and community settings. BMJ 2012;345:e5205 22 22 Gawande A. Being Mortal: Illness, Medicine and What Matters in the End. London: Profile Books Ltd 2014: 243 23 Williams A. The value of QALYs. Health and Social Service Journal 1985;94(4957suppl):3-5 24 World Health Organization. World report on ageing and health. 2015. http://apps.who.int/iris/bitstream/10665/186463/1/978924094811_eng.pdf? ua=1 (accessed December 2015) at p.30 25 Marengoni A, Angleman S, Mells R, et al. Aging with multimorbidity: A systematic review of the literature. Ageing Research Reviews 2011;10(4):430- 439 26 World Health Organization. World report on ageing and health. 2015. http://apps.who.int/iris/bitstream/10665/186463/1/978924094811_eng.pdf? ua=1 (accessed December 2015) at p.4 27 National Health Service. The NHS Schedule. http://www.nhs.uk/conditions/vaccinations/pages/vaccination-schedule-age- checklist.aspx (accessed December 2015) http://apps.who.int/iris/bitstream/10665/186463/1/978924094811_eng.pdf?ua=1 http://apps.who.int/iris/bitstream/10665/186463/1/978924094811_eng.pdf?ua=1 http://apps.who.int/iris/bitstream/10665/186463/1/978924094811_eng.pdf?ua=1 http://apps.who.int/iris/bitstream/10665/186463/1/978924094811_eng.pdf?ua=1 http://www.nhs.uk/conditions/vaccinations/pages/vaccination-schedule-age-checklist.aspx http://www.nhs.uk/conditions/vaccinations/pages/vaccination-schedule-age-checklist.aspx 23 28 National Institute for Health and Care Excellence. Falls in older people: assessing risk and prevention. 2013. http://www.nice.org.uk/guidance/cg161 (accessed December 2015) 29 Hughes JC. Ethical issues and health care for older people. In Ashcroft RE, Dawson A, Draper H, et al, eds. Principles of Health Care Ethics Second Edition. Chichester: John Wiley and Sons Ltd 2007: 469-474 http://www.nice.org.uk/guidance/cg161 work_5c2bmhotdvh2xkj2rlm5ttkkua ---- Restorative Justice: The Real Story Restorative justice: the real story Kathleen Daly School of Criminology and Criminal Justice Mt Gravatt Campus Griffith University Brisbane, Queensland 4111 Australia +61 7 3875-5625 (of); 3875-5608 (fax) 3216-1630 (ho) k.daly@mailbox.gu.edu.au Version Revised 2 May 2001 Paper revised from that presented to the Scottish Criminology Conference, Edinburgh, 21-22 September 2000. [to add more on acknowledgments later] Biographical note: Kathleen Daly is Associate Professor in the School of Criminology and Criminal Justice at Griffith University (Brisbane). Her interests are on gender and race in crime, justice, and criminology, and her current research is on restorative justice. Key words: restorative justice, conferencing, retributive justice, myths about justice 1 Restorative justice: the real story Abstract Advocates' claims about restorative justice contain four myths: (1) restorative justice is the opposite of retributive justice, (2) restorative justice uses indigenous justice practices and was the dominant form of pre-modern justice, (3) restorative justice is a 'care' (or feminine) response to crime in comparison to a 'justice' (or masculine) response, and (4) restorative justice can be expected to produce major changes in people. Drawing from research on conferencing in Australia and New Zealand, I show that the 'real story' of restorative justice differs greatly from advocates' mythical 'true story'. Despite what advocates say, there are connections between retribution and restoration (or reparation), restorative justice should not be considered a pre-modern and 'feminine' justice, strong stories of repair and goodwill are uncommon, and the raw material for 'restorativeness' between victims and offenders may be in short supply. Following Engel (1993), myth refers to a true story; its truth deals with 'origins ... with how something came to be'. Origin stories, in turn, 'encode a set of oppositions' such that when telling a true story, speakers transcend adversity. By comparing advocates' true story of restorative justice with the real story, I offer a critical and sympathetic reading of advocates' efforts to move the idea forward. I end by reflecting on whether the political future of restorative justice is better secured by telling the mythical true story or the real story. 2 Restorative justice: the real story INTRODUCTION Much has been written in recent years that damns and sings the praises of restorative justice. In contrast to the voluminous critical and advocacy literatures, there is a thin empirical record of what is happening on the ground. i The aim of this paper is to present the 'real story' of restorative justice, one that reflects what has been learned from research on conferencing ii in Australia and New Zealand. I am being mostly, although not entirely, ironic in proposing to tell the real story of restorative justice. There are many stories and no real one. I shall recount what I have learned on my journey in the field, which began in the early 1990s (Braithwaite and Daly, 1994) and intensified in 1995 when I moved to Australia to work with restorative justice researchers at the Australian National University and to initiate my own program of research. It has taken me some time to understand and make sense of the idea of restorative justice. When I arrived in Australia, my questions centred on what was happening in the conference process. What were victims, offenders, and their supporters saying to each other? How did they relate to one another? What did the professionals (the coordinators and police) think was going on? Did the critiques of conferencing, especially by feminist and anti-racist analysts, have merit? I began to observe conferences in 1995; since then, I have observed close to 60 of them; and as part of a major project on conferencing in South Australia, members of my research group and I observed 89 youth justice conferences and interviewed over 170 young people (offenders) and victims associated with them, in 1998 and again, in 1999 (Daly et al., 1998; Daly, 2001b). The more I observed and talked with those involved, attended professional meetings, and read about restorative justice, the more perplexed I became. I discovered that there was a substantial gap between what I observed in conferences and what both the advocates and 3 critics were saying about restorative justice. This is what moves me to tell the real story, and I do so by analysing four myths that feature in advocates' stories and claims: 1. Restorative justice is the opposite of retributive justice. 2. Restorative justice uses indigenous justice practices and was the dominant form of pre-modern justice. 3. Restorative justice is a 'care' (or feminine) response to crime in comparison to a 'justice' (or masculine) response. 4. Restorative justice can be expected to produce major changes in people. Although I focus on advocates' claims, there can be as much distortion by the critics, as well. Moreover, there are debates among the advocates on the meaning and practice of restorative justice; thus, my characterisation of the advocacy position is somewhat of a caricature. I use the concept of myth in two ways. First, myth can be understood simply as a partial truth, a distorted characterisation that requires correction by historical or contemporary evidence. Second, myth can be understood as a special form of narrative. Following Engel (1993: 790-92), myth 'refers not to fantasy or fiction but to a "true story" ... which is sacred, exemplary, significant'. 'The "truth" of myth differs from the "truth" of historical or scientific accounts'. Engel suggests that myths 'differ from other forms of storytelling' in that they 'deal with origins, with birth, with beginnings ... with "how something ... began to be"'. He discovers in his analysis of the 'origin stories' of parents of children with disabilities that they 'perceive the world in terms of a set of oppositions that originate in the diagnosis of their child' (p. 821). A recurring origin story is that the professional (a doctor) is wrong about the initial diagnosis, and 'the parent's insights have ultimately triumphed over those of the professional' (p. 821). As such, when parents retell their stories, 'the triumphant ending will be achieved again'. 'The very act of retelling is a way to ensure that ... values and outcomes in the myth will triumph over pain, opposition, and disorder'. Engel says that this 4 sense of triumph reveals the 'affirmative, creative power of myth', where myth 'abolishes time' and 'the work of myth [transcends adversity]' (pp. 823-24). When I began to write this paper, I used the concept of myth as partial truth, a foil against which I could write a more authoritative story. But as I began to analyse the myths, I began to see them in a different light, in Engel's terms, as origin stories that 'encode a set of oppositions' (p. 822). While I shall spend more analytical time telling the real story of restorative justice, using myth as partial truth, I also offer a sympathetic reading of advocates' true story of restorative justice by viewing myth as a creative device to transcend adversity. I end by reflecting on whether the political future of restorative justice is better secured by telling the real story or the mythical true story. THE PROBLEM OF DEFINITION Restorative justice is not one thing, but an umbrella concept that refers to diverse practices to resolve disputes in schools and workplaces, to respond to crime, and to make decisions in the care and protection or child welfare areas. For juvenile and criminal cases, it is used primarily when people have admitted to an offence; it therefore focuses on the penalty, not fact-finding phase of the adjudication process. Restorative justice can refer to diversion from formal court process, to actions taken in parallel with court decisions, and to meetings between victims and offenders at any stage of the criminal process, including an offender's release from prison. The word is now being applied after the fact to programs and policies that have been in place for some time. The idea of restorative justice has proved to be enormously popular with governments, who now wish to package a range of police responses and correctional programs as 'restorative' (e.g., LaPrairie, 1999 for Canada; Crawford, 2001 for England and Wales). While it is not possible to have a precise definition that covers a diverse array of practices across a range of decision-making sites, both in and outside of 5 institutions of criminal justice, a general definition might be this: those with a stake in a crime (typically a victim, an offender, and their supporters) come together to discuss the offence and its impact, and they decide what to do to 'repair the harm' to the victim and perhaps also to a larger collectivity. McCold (1999/2000) constructed a venn diagram to distinguish practices that he considers to be fully, mostly, or only partly restorative. iii He suggests that fully restorative practices occur at the intersection of the three circles of 'victim reparation', 'offender responsibility', and 'communities of care reconciliation'. At that intersection, there are peace circles (or sentencing circles) and conferences of various types. Outside that intersection are other recent practices (e.g., truth and reconciliation commissions, reparative boards), as well as those that have been around for some time (e.g., youth aid panels and victim services). Using McCold's definition, the research reviewed here and the jurisdictions I have studied use 'fully restorative' practices. MYTHS ABOUT RESTORATIVE JUSTICE Myth 1. Restorative justice is the opposite of retributive justice. When one first dips into the restorative justice literature, the first thing one 'learns' is that restorative justice differs sharply from retributive justice. It is said that  restorative justice focuses on repairing the harm caused by crime, whereas retributive justice focuses on punishing an offence;  restorative justice is characterised by dialogue and negotiation among the parties, whereas retributive justice is characterised by adversarial relations among the parties; and  restorative justice assumes that community members or organisations take a more active role, whereas for retributive justice, 'the community' is represented by the state. 6 Most striking is that all the elements associated with restorative justice are good, whereas all those associated with retributive justice are bad. The retributive-restorative oppositional contrast is not only made by restorative justice advocates, but increasingly one finds it canonised in criminology and juvenile justice textbooks. The question arises, is it right? On empirical and normative grounds, I suggest that in characterising justice aims and practices, it is neither accurate nor defensible. Despite advocates' well-meaning intentions, the contrast is a simple sales pitch to market the superiority of their justice 'products'. To do that, definite boundaries are marked between the good (restorative), the bad (retributive), and the ugly (rehabilitative) types of justice. Advocates seem to assume that an ideal justice system should be of one type only, that it should be pure and not 'contaminated' by or mixed with others. Before demonstrating the problems with this position, I give a sympathetic reading of what I think advocates are trying to say. Mead's (1917-18) "The psychology of punitive justice" contrasts two methods of responding to crime. One he termed 'the attitude of hostility toward the lawbreaker' (p. 227), which 'brings with it the attitudes of retribution, repression, and exclusion" (pp. 226-27) and which sees a lawbreaker as 'enemy'. The other, exemplified in the (then) emerging juvenile court, is the 'reconstructive attitude' (p. 234), which tries to 'understand the causes of social and individual breakdown, to mend ... the defective situation', to determine responsibility 'not to place punishment but to obtain future results' (p. 231). Most restorative justice advocates see the justice world through this Meadian lens; they reject the 'attitude of hostility toward the lawbreaker', do not wish to view him or her as 'enemy', and desire an alternative kind of justice. On that score, I concur, as most readers and researchers no doubt would. However, the 'attitude of hostility' is a caricature of criminal justice, which over the last century and a half has wavered between desires to 'treat' some and 'punish' others, and which surely cannot be encapsulated in the one term, 'retributive justice'. By framing justice aims (or principles) 7 and practices in oppositional terms, restorative justice advocates not only do a disservice to history, they also give a restricted view of the present. They assume that restorative justice practices should exclude elements of retribution; and in rejecting an 'attitude of hostility', they assume that retribution as a justice principle must also be rejected. When observing conferences, I discovered that participants engaged in a flexible incorporation of multiple justice aims, which included:  some elements of retributive justice (that is, censure for past offences),  some elements of rehabilitative justice (for example, by asking, what shall we do to encourage future law-abiding behaviour?) and  some elements of restorative justice (for example, by asking, how can the offender make up for what he or she did to the victim?) When I related these findings to colleagues, one said, 'yes, this is a problem'. This speaker's concern was that as restorative justice was being incorporated into the regular justice system, it would turn out to be a set of 'simple techniques', rather than an 'ideal of justice ... in an ideal of society' (Walgrave, 1995: 240, 245) and that its core values would be lost. Another said (paraphrasing), 'retribution may well be present now in conferences, but you wouldn't want to make the argument that it should be present' (Braithwaite, personal communication). These comments provoked me to consider the relationship between restorative and retributive justice, and the role of punishment in restorative justice, in normative terms. Distilling from other papers (e.g., Daly and Immarigeon, 1998: 32-35; Daly, 2000a, 2000b) and arguments by Duff (1992, 1996, 2001), Hampton (1998), and Zedner (1994), I have come to see that apparently contrary principles of retribution and reparation should be viewed as dependent on one another. Retributive censure should ideally occur before reparative gestures (or a victim's interest or movement to negotiate these) are possible in an ethical or psychological sense. Both censure and reparation may be experienced as 'punishment' by 8 offenders (even if this is not the intent of decision-makers), and both censure and reparation need to occur before a victim or community can 'reintegrate' the offender into the community. These complex and contingent interactions are expressed in varied ways and should not be viewed as having to follow any one fixed sequence. Moreover, one cannot assume that subsequent actions, such as the victim's forgiving the offender or a reconciliation of victim and offender (or others), should occur. In the advocacy literature, however, one finds that there is too quick a move to 'repair the harm', 'heal those injured by crime' or to 're-integrate offenders', passing over a crucial phase of 'holding offenders accountable', which is the retributive part of the process. A major block in communicating ideas about the relationship of retributive to restorative justice is that there is great variability in how people understand and use key terms such as punishment and retribution. Some argue that incarceration and fines are punishments because they are intended deprivations, whereas probation or a reparative measure such as doing work for a crime victim are not punishment because they are intended to be constructive (Wright, 1991). Others define punishment more broadly to include anything that is unpleasant, a burden, or an imposition of some sort; the intentions of the decision-maker are less significant (Duff, 1992, 2001; Davis, 1992). Some use retribution to describe a justification for punishment (i.e., intended to be in proportion to the harm caused), whereas others use it to describe a form of punishment (i.e., intended to be of a type that is harsh or painful). iv On proportionality, restorative justice advocates take different positions: some (e.g., Braithwaite and Pettit, 1990) eschew retributivism, favouring instead a free-ranging consequentialist justification and highly individualised responses, while others wish to limit restorative justice responses to a desert-based, proportionate criteria (Walgrave and Aertsen, 1996; Van Ness, 1993). For the form of punishment, some use retribution in a neutral way to refer to a censuring of harms (e.g., Duff, 1996), whereas most use the term to 9 connote a punitive response, which is associated with emotions of revenge or intentions to inflict pain on wrong-doers (Wright, 1991). I shall not attempt to adjudicate these competing claims; the sources of antagonism lie in varied definitions and the different images these definitions conjure in people's heads about justice relations and practices. However, one way to gain some clarity is to conceptualise punishment, retribution, and punitive (and their "non" counterparts) as separate dimensions, each having its own continuum of meaning, rather than to conflate them, as now typically occurs in the literature. Because the terms 'retributive' and 'restorative' justice have such strong meanings and referents, and are used largely by advocates (and others) as metaphors for the bad and the good justice, perhaps they should be jettisoned in analysing current and future justice practices. Instead, we might refer to 'older' and 'newer' justice forms. These terms do not provide a content to justice principles or practices, but they do offer a way to depict developments in the justice field with an eye to history and with an appreciation that any 'new' justice practice will have many bits of the 'old' in it. v The terms also permit description and explanation of a larger phenomenon, that is, of a profound transformation of justice forms and practices now occurring in most developed societies in the West, and certainly the English-speaking ones of which I am aware. Restorative justice is only a part of that transformation. By the old justice, I refer to modern practices of courthouse justice, which permit no interaction between victim and offender, where legal actors and other experts do the talking and make decisions, and whose (stated) aim is to punish, or at times, reform an offender. By the new justice, vi I refer to a variety of recent practices, which normally bring victims and offenders (and others) together in a process in which both lay and legal actors make decisions, and whose (stated) aim is to repair the harm for victims, offenders, and perhaps other members of 'the community' in ways that matter to them. (While the stated aim of 10 either justice form may be to 'punish the crime' or 'repair the harm', we should expect to see mixed justice aims in participants' justice talk and practices.) vii New justice practices are one of several developments in a larger justice field, which also includes the 'new penology' (Feeley and Simon, 1992) and 'unthinkable punishment policies' (Tonry, 1999). The field is fragmented and moving in contradictory directions (Crawford, 1997; Garland, 1996; O'Malley, 1999; Pratt, 2000). Myth 2. Restorative justice uses indigenous justice practices and was the dominant form of pre-modern justice. A common theme in the restorative justice literature is that this reputedly 'new' justice form is 'really not new' (Consedine, 1995: 12). As Consedine puts it, Biblical justice was restorative. So too was justice in most indigenous cultures. In pre-colonial New Zealand, Maori had a fully integrated system of restorative justice ... It was the traditional philosophy of Pacific nations such as Tonga, Fiji and Samoa. ... In pre-Norman Ireland, restorative justice was interwoven ... with the fabric of daily life ... (p. 12). Braithwaite (1999: 1) argues that restorative justice is 'ground[ed] in traditions of justice from the ancient Arab, Greek, and Roman civilisations that accepted a restorative approach even to homicide'. He continues with a large sweep of human history, citing the 'public assemblies ... of the Germanic peoples', 'Indian Hindu [traditions in] 6000-2000 B.C.', and 'ancient Buddhist, Taoist, and Confucian traditions ...'; and he concludes that 'restorative justice has been the dominant model of criminal justice throughout most of human history for all the world's peoples' (p. 1, emphasis added). What an extraordinary claim! 11 Linked with the claim that restorative justice has been the dominant form of criminal justice throughout human history is the claim that present-day indigenous justice practices fall within the restorative justice rubric. Thus, for example, Consedine (1995: 99) says A new paradigm of justice is operating [in New Zealand], which is very traditional in its philosophy, yet revolutionary in its effects. A restorative philosophy of justice has replaced a retributive one. Ironically, 150 years after the traditional Maori restorative praxis was abolished in Aotearoa, youth justice policy is once again operating from the same philosophy. Reverence for and romanticisation of an indigenous past slides over practices that the modern 'civilised' Western mind would object to, such as a variety of harsh physical (bodily) punishments and banishment. At the same time, the modern Western mind may not be able to grasp how certain 'harsh punishments' have been sensible within the terms of a particular culture. Weitekamp (1999: 93) combines 'ancient forms' of justice practice (as restorative) and indigenous groups' current practices (as restorative) when he says that some of the new[] ... programs are in fact very old. ... [A]ncient forms of restorative justice have been used in [non-state] societies and by early forms of humankind. [F]amily group conferences [and] ... circle hearings [have been used] by indigenous people such as the Aboriginals, the Inuit, and the native Indians of North and South America. ... It is kind of ironic that we have at [the turn of this century] to go back to methods and forms of conflict resolution which were practiced some millennia ago by our ancestors ... I confess to a limited knowledge of justice practices and systems throughout the history of humankind. What I know is confined mainly to the past three centuries and to developments in the United States and several other countries. Thus, in addressing this 12 myth, I do so from a position of ignorance in knowing only a small portion of history. Upon reflection, however, my lack of historical knowledge may not matter. All that is required is the realisation that advocates do not intend to write authoritative histories of justice. Rather, they are constructing 'origin myths' about restorative justice. If the first form of human justice was restorative justice, then advocates can claim a need to recover it from a history of 'takeover' by state-sponsored retributive justice. And, by identifying current indigenous practices as restorative justice, advocates can claim a need to recover these practices from a history of 'takeover' by white colonial powers who instituted retributive justice. Thus, the history of justice practices is re-written by advocates not only to authorise restorative justice as the first human form of justice, but also a form of justice that is congenial to modern-day indigenous and, as we shall see in myth 3, feminist social movements for justice. In the restorative justice field, most commentators focus specifically (and narrowly) on changes that occurred over a 400-year period (8th to 11th centuries) in England (and some European countries), where a system of largely kin-based dispute settlement gave way to a court system, in which feudal lords retained a portion of property forfeited by an offender. In England, this loose system was centralised and consolidated during the century following the Norman Invasion in 1066, as the development of state (crown) law depended on the collection of revenues collected by judges for the king. For restorative justice advocates, the transformation of disputes as offences between individuals to offences against the state is one element that marked the end of pre-modern forms of restorative justice. A second element is the decline in compensation to the victim for the losses from a crime (Weitekamp, 1999). Advocates' constructions of the history of restorative justice, that is, the origin myth that a superior justice form prevailed before the imposition of retributive justice, is linked to their desire to maintain a strong oppositional contrast between retributive and restorative 13 justice. That is to say, the origin myth and oppositional contrast are both required in telling the true story of restorative justice. I do not see bad faith at work here. Rather, advocates are trying to move an idea into the political and policy arena, and this may necessitate having to utilise a simple contrast of the good and the bad justice, along with an origin myth of how it all began. What does concern me is a smoothing over and a lumping together in one justice form the specific histories and practices of justice in pre-modern societies. Is it appropriate to refer to all of these justice practices 'restorative'? What, in fact, do they have in common? What is gained, and more importantly, what is lost by this homogenising move? Efforts to write histories of restorative justice, where a pre-modern past is romantically (and selectively) invoked to justify a current justice practice, are not only in error, but also unwittingly reinscribe an ethnocentrism their authors wish to avoid. As Blagg (1997) and Cain (2000) point out, there has been an orientalist appropriation of indigenous justice practices, largely in the service of strengthening advocates' positions. A common, albeit erroneous, claim is that conferencing 'has its direct roots in Maori culture' (Shearing, 2001: 218, note 5; see also Consedine, 1995). The real story is that conferencing emerged in the 1980s, in the context of Maori political challenges to white New Zealanders and to their welfare and criminal justice system. Investing decision-making practices with Maori cultural values meant that family groups (whanau) should have a greater say in what happens, that venues should be culturally appropriate, and that processes should accommodate a mix of culturally appropriate practices. New Zealand's minority group population includes not only the Maori but also Pacific Island Polynesians. Therefore, with the introduction of conferencing, came awareness of the need to incorporate different elements of 'cultural appropriateness' into the conference process. But the devising of a (white, bureaucratic) justice practice that is flexible and accommodating toward cultural 14 differences does not mean that conferencing is an indigenous justice practice. Maxwell and Morris (1993: 4), who know the New Zealand situation well, are clear on this point: A distinction must be drawn between a system which attempts to re-establish the indigenous model of pre-European times and a system of justice which is culturally appropriate. The New Zealand system is an attempt to establish the latter, not to replicate the former. As such, it seeks to incorporate many of the features apparent in whanau decision-making processes and seen in meetings on marae today, but it also contains elements quite alien to indigenous models. Conferencing is better understood as a fragmented justice form: it splices white, bureaucratic forms of justice with elements of informal justice that may include non-white (or non-Western) values or methods of judgment, with all the attendant dangers of such 'spliced justice' (Daly, 1998; Findlay, 2000; Pavlich, 1996). With the flexibility of informal justice, practitioners, advocates, and members of minority groups may see the potential for introducing culturally sensible and responsive forms of justice. But to say that conferencing is an indigenous justice practice (or 'has its roots in indigenous justice') is to re-engage a white-centred view of the world. And, as Blagg (1997) suggests, it may lead to a 'double failure' for members of indigenous groups: not only will they appear to have 'failed' to act in a law-abiding fashion, and but also they will appear to have 'failed' to act appropriately as indigenous people according to a white-centred justice script. Myth 3. Restorative justice is a 'care' (or feminine) response to crime in comparison to a 'justice' (or masculine) response. Myths 2 and 3 have a similar oppositional logic, but play with different dichotomies. The following chart shows the terms that are often linked to restorative and retributive justice. 15 restorative justice retributive justice pre-modern modern indigenous (informal) state (formal) feminine (care) masculine (justice) eastern (Japan) western (US) superior justice inferior justice Note here the power inversion, essential to the origin myth of restorative justice, where the subordinated or marginalised groups (pre-modern, indigenous, feminine) are aligned with the more superior justice form. Many readers will be familiar with the 'care' and 'justice' dichotomy. It was put forward by Carol Gilligan in her hughly popular book, In a Different Voice (1982). For about a decade, it seemed that most feminist legal theory articles were organised around the 'difference' versus 'dominance' perspectives of Gilligan and MacKinnon, respectively. In criminology, Heidensohn (1986) and Harris (1987) attempted to apply the care/justice dichotomy to the criminal justice system. I came into this debate in 1989, saying that we should challenge the association of justice and care reasoning with male/masculine and female/feminine voices, respectively (Daly, 1989). I suggested that this gender-linked association was not accurate empirically, and argued that it would be misleading to think that an alternative to men's forms of criminal law and justice practices could be found by adding women's voice or reconstituting the system along the lines of an ethic of care. But the different voice is back! Now the 'ethic of care' (Persephone) is pitched as the alternative to retributive justice (Portia). Masters and Smith (1998) attempt to demonstrate that Persephone, the voice of caring, is evident in a variety of restorative responses to crime. Their arguments confuse, however, because they argue that Persephone is 'informed by an ethic of care as well as an ethic of justice' (p. 11). And toward the end of the article, they say 16 'we cannot do without Portia (ethic of justice), but neither can we do without Persephone' (p. 21). Thus, it is not clear whether, within the terms of their argument, Persephone stands for the feminine or includes both the masculine and feminine, or whether we need both Portia and Persephone. They apparently agree with all three positions. They also see little difference between a 'feminine' and a 'feminist approach', terms that they use interchangeably. In general, they normally credit 'relational justice as a distinctly feminine approach to crime and conflict' (p. 13). They say that 'reintegrative shaming can be considered a feminine (or Persephone) theory' and that there is a 'fit between reintegrative shaming practice and the feminist ethic of care' (p. 13, my italics since the authors have shifted from a feminine ethic to a feminist ethic). Toward the end of the paper, they make the astonishing claim, one that I suspect my colleague John Braithwaite would find difficult to accept, that 'reintegrative shaming is perhaps the first feminist criminological theory'. They argue this is so because the 'practice of reintegrative shaming can be interpreted as being grounded in a feminine, rather than a masculine understanding of the social world' (p. 20). There is a lot to unpick here, and I shall not go point by point. Nor do I wish to undermine the spirit of the paper since the authors' intentions are laudable, in particular, their desire to define a more progressive way to respond to crime. My concern is that using gender dichotomies, or any dichotomies for that matter, to describe principles and practices of justice will always fail us, will always lead to great disappointment. viii Traditional courthouse justice works with the abstraction of criminal law, but must deal with the messy world of people's lives, and hence, must deal with context and relations. 'Care' responses to some offenders can re-victimise some victims; they may be helpful in some cases or for some offenders or for some victims or they may also be oppressive and unjust for other offenders and victims. Likewise, with so-called 'justice' responses. The set of terms lined up along the 'male/masculine' and 'female/feminine' poles is long and varied: some terms are about 17 process, others with modes of response (e.g., repair the harm), and still others, with ways of thinking about culpability for the harm. ix I am struck by the frequency with which people use dichotomies such as the male and female voice, retributive and restorative justice, or West and East, to depict justice principles and practices. Such dichotomies are also used to construct normative positions about justice, where it is assumed (I think wrongly) that the sensibility of one side of the dualism necessarily excludes (or is antithetical to) the sensibility of the other. Increasingly, scholars are coming to see the value of theorising justice in hybrid terms, of seeing connections between apparent oppositions (see e.g., Bottoms, 1998; Daly, 2000a; Duff, 2001; Hudson, 1998; Zedner, 1994). Like the advocates promoting Myth 2, those promoting Myth 3 want to emphasise the importance of identifying a different response to crime than the one currently in use. I am certainly on the side of that aspiration. However, I cannot agree with the terms in which the position has been argued and sold to academic audiences and wider publics. There is a loss of credibility when analyses do not move beyond oppositional justice metaphors, when claims are imprecise, and when extraordinary tales of repair and goodwill are assumed to be typical of the restorative justice experience. Myth 4. Restorative justice can be expected to produce major changes in people. I have said that attention needs to be given to the 'reality on the ground', to what is actually happening in, and resulting from, practices termed 'restorative justice'. There are several levels to describe and analyse what is going on; first, what happens in the justice practice itself; second, the relationship between it and the broader justice system; and third, how restorative justice is located within the broader politics of crime control. I focus on the first level and present two forms of evidence: (1) stories of dramatic transformations or moving 18 accounts of reconciliation and (2) aggregated information across a larger number of cases, drawing from research on conference observations and interviews with participants. Stories of restorative justice Consedine (1995: 9) opens his book by excerpting from a 1993 New Zealand news story: The families of two South Auckland boys killed by a car welcomed the accused driver yesterday with open arms and forgiveness. The young man, who gave himself up to the police yesterday morning, apologised to the families and was ceremonially reunited with the Tongan and Samoan communities at a special ser vice last night. The 20-year old Samoan visited the Tongan families after his court appearance to apologise for the deaths of the two children in Mangere. The Tongan and Samoan communities of Mangere later gathered at the Tongan Methodist Church in a service of reconciliation. The young man sat at the feast table flanked by the mothers of the dead boys. Consedine says further that this case provides 'ample evidence of the power that healing and forgiveness can play in our daily lives. ... The grieving Tongan and Samoan communities simply embraced the young driver ... and forgave him. His deep shame, his fear, his sorrow, his alienation from the community was resolved' (p. 162). Another example comes from Umbreit (1994: 1). His book opens with the story of Linda and Bob Jackson, whose house was broken into; they subsequently met with the offender as part of his sentencing disposition. The offender, Allan, 'felt better after the mediation ... he was able to make amends to the Jacksons'. Moreover, 'Linda and Bob felt less vulnerable, were able to sleep better and received payment for their losses. All parties were able to put this event behind them'. Later in the book, Umbreit (1994: 197-202) offers 19 another case study of a second couple, Bob and Anne, after their house was burglarised a second time. He summarises the outcome this way: Bob, Anne, and Jim [the offender] felt the mediation process and outcome was fair. All were very satisfied with participation in the program. Rather than playing passive roles ... [they] actively participated in 'making things right'. During a subsequent conversation with Bob, he commented that 'this was the first time (after several victimisations) that I ever felt any sense of fairness. The courts always ignored me before. They didn't care about my concerns. And Jim isn't such a bad kid after all, was he?' Jim also indicated that he felt better after the mediation and more aware of the impact the burglary had on Bob and Anne (p. 202). Lastly, there is the fable of Sam, an adolescent offender who attended a diversionary conference, which was first related by Braithwaite (1996) and retold by Shearing (2001: 214-215). Braithwaite (1996: 2) says that his story is a 'composite of several Sams I have seen'; thus, while he admits that it is not a real story of Sam, it is said to show the 'essential features ... of restorative justice' (Shearing 2001: 214). This is something like a building contractor saying to a potential home buyer, 'this is a composite of the house I can build for you; it's not the real house, but it's like many houses I have sold to happy buyers over the years'. What the composite gives and what the building contractor offers us is a vision of the possible, of the perfect house. Whether the house can ever be built is less important than imagining its possibility and its perfection. This is the cornerstone of the true story of restorative justice, like many proposed justice innovations of the past. Sam's story, as told by Braithwaite, is longer than I give here, and thus, I leave out emotional details that make any story compelling. Sam, who is homeless and says he was abused by his parents, has no one who really cares about him except his older sister, his former hockey coach at school, and his Uncle George. These people attend the conference, 20 along with the elderly female victim and her daughter. Sam says he knocked over the victim and took her purse because he needed the money. His significant others rebuke him for doing this, but also remember that he had a good side before he started getting into trouble. The victim and daughter describe the effects of the robbery, but Sam does not seem to be affected. After his apparent callous response to the victim, Sam's sister cries, and during a break, she reveals that she too had been abused by their parents. When the conference reconvenes, Sam's sister speaks directly to Sam, and without mentioning details, says she understands what Sam went through. The victim appreciates what is being said and begins to cry. Sam's callous exterior begins to crumble. He says he wants to do something for the victim, but doesn't know what he can do without a home or job. His sister offers her place for him to stay, and the coach says he can offer some him work. At the end of the conference, the victim hugs Sam and tearfully says good luck, Sam apologises again, and Uncle George says he will continue to help Sam and his sister when needed. Many questions arise in reading stories like these. How often do expressions of kindness and understanding, of movement toward repair and goodwill, actually occur? What are the typical 'effects' on participants? Is the perfect house of restorative justice ever built? Another kind of evidence, aggregated data across a larger number of cases, can provide some answers. Statistical aggregates of restorative justice Here are some highlights of what has been learned from research on youth justice conferences in Australia and New Zealand. x Official data show that about 85-90 percent of conferences resulted in agreed outcomes, and 80 percent of young people completed their agreements. From New Zealand research in the early 1990s (Maxwell and Morris 1993), conferences appeared to be largely offender-centred events. Just half of victims attended 21 conferences, and of all the groups involved, victims were the least satisfied with what happened. Maxwell and Morris (1996:95-96) also reported that 'the new system remains largely unresponsive to cultural differences' in handling Maori cases, which they argue is a consequence, in part, of too few resources. The most robust finding across all the studies in the region is that conferences receive very high marks along dimensions of procedural justice, that is, victims and offenders view the process and the outcomes as fair. In the Re-Integrative Shaming Experiments (RISE) in Canberra, admitted offenders were randomly assigned to court and conference. Strang et al. (1999) have reported the following findings to date. Compared to those offenders who went to court, those going to conferences have higher levels of procedural justice, higher levels of restorative justice, and an increased respect for the police and law. Compared to victims whose cases went to court, conference victims have higher levels of recovery from the offence. Conference victims also had high levels of procedural justice, but they could not be compared to court victims, who rarely attended court proceedings. The RISE findings are important because they give us an indication of the relative merits of a conference or court proceeding. Few other projects can do this. Like other studies, the South Australia Juvenile Justice (SAJJ) Research on Conferencing Project finds very high levels of procedural justice registered by offenders and victims at conferences. To items such as, were you treated fairly, were you treated with respect, did you have a say in the agreement, among others, 80 to 95 percent of victims and offenders said that they were treated fairly and had a say. In light of the procedural justice literature, these findings are of interest because, as the argument goes, when citizens perceive a legal process as fair, when they are listened to and treated with respect, there is an affirmation of the legitimacy of the legal order. 22 Compared to the high levels of perceived procedural justice, the SAJJ project finds relatively less evidence of restorativeness. The measures of restorativeness tapped the degree to which offenders and victims recognised the other and were affected by the other; they focused on the degree to which there was positive movement between the offender and victim and their supporters during the conference (the SAJJ measures are more concrete and relational measures of restorativeness than those used in RISE). Whereas very high proportions of victims and offenders (80 to 95 percent) said that the process was fair (among other variables taping procedural justice), 'restorativeness' was evident in 30 to 50 percent of conferences (depending on the item), and solidly in no more than about one-third. Thus, in this jurisdiction where conferences are used routinely, xi fairness can more easily be achieved than restorativeness. As but one example, from the interviews we learned that from the victims' perspectives, less than 30 percent of offenders were perceived as making genuine apologies, but from the offenders' perspectives, close to 60 percent said their apology was genuine. These results lead me to think that young people (offenders) and victims orient themselves to a conference and what they hope to achieve in it in ways different that the advocacy literature imagines. The stance of empathy and openness to 'the other', the expectation of being able to speak and reflect on one's actions, and the presence of new justice norms (or language) emphasising 'repair' -- all of these are novel cultural elements for most participants. Young people appear to be as, if not more, interested in repairing their own reputations than in repairing the harm to victims. Among the most important things that the victims hoped would occur at the conference was for the offender to hear how the offence affected them, but half the offenders told us that the victim's story had no effect or only a little effect on them. 23 How often, then, does the exceptional or 'nirvana' story of repair and goodwill occur? I devised a measure that combined the SAJJ observer's judgment of the degree to which a conference 'ended on a high, a positive note of repair and good will' with one that rated the conference on a 5-point scale from poor to exceptional. While the first tapped the degree to which there was movement between victims and offenders toward the 'other', the second tapped a more general feeling about the conference dynamics and how well the conference was managed by the coordinator. With this combined measure, 10 percent of conferences were rated very highly, another 40 percent, good; and the rest, a mixed or poor rating. If conferencing is used routinely (not just in a select set of cases), I suspect that the story of Sam and Uncle George will be infrequent; it may happen 10 percent of the time, if that. Assessing the 'effects' of conferences on participants is complex because such effects change over time and, for victims, they are contingent on whether offenders come through on promises made. I present findings on victims' sense of having 'recovered' from the offence and on young people's re-offending in the post-conference period. In the Year 2 (1999) interviews with victims, over 60 percent said they had 'fully recovered' from the offence, that it was 'all behind' them. Their recovery was more likely when offenders completed the agreement than when they did not, but recovery was only partly influenced by the conference and an offender's behaviour. As important, they said, was the 'passage of time' and 'self-resources' such as their own resilience. However, conferences can have positive 'effects' on reducing victims' anger toward and fear of offenders. Drawing from the victim interviews in 1998 and 1999, over 75 percent of victims felt angry toward the offender before the conference, but this dropped to 44 percent after the conference and was 39 percent a year later. Close to 40 percent of victims were frightened of the offender before the conference, but this dropped to 25 percent after the conference and was 18 percent a year later. 24 Therefore, for victims, meeting offenders in the conference setting can have beneficial results. The conference effect everyone asks about is, does it reduce re-offending? Proof (or disproof) of reductions in re-offending from conferences (compared not only to court, but to other interventions such as formal caution, other diversion approaches, or no legal action at all) will not be available for a long time, if ever. The honest answer to the re-offending question is 'we'll probably never know' because the amounts of money would be exorbitant and research methods using experimental designs judged too 'risky' in an ethical and political sense. To date, there have been three studies of conferencing and re-offending in Australia and New Zealand, one of which compares re-offending for a sample of offenders randomly assigned to conference and court and two that explore whether re-offending can be linked to things that occur in conferences. xii The RISE project finds that for one of four major offence categories studied (violent offences compared to drink driving, property offences, shoplifting), those offenders who were assigned to a conference had a significantly reduced rate of re-offending than those who were assigned to court (Sherman, Strang, and Woods, 2000). As others have said (Abel, 1982: 278; Levrant et al., 1999: 17-22), there is a great faith placed on the conference process to change young offenders, when the conditions of their day to day lives, which may be conducive to getting into trouble, may not change at all. The SAJJ project asked if there were things that occurred in conferences that could predict re-offending, over and above those variables known to be conducive to lawbreaking (and its detection): past offending and social marginality (Hayes and Daly, 2001). In a regression analysis, we found that over and above the young person's race-ethnicity (Aboriginal or non-Aboriginal), sex, whether s/he offended prior to the offence that led to the SAJJ 25 conference, and a measure of the young person's mobility and marginality, there were two conference elements associated with re-offending. When young people were remorseful and when outcomes were achieved by genuine consensus, they were less likely to re-offend during an 8- to 12-month period after the conference. These results are remarkably similar to those of Maxwell and Morris (2000) in their study of re-offending in New Zealand. They found that what happens in conferences (e.g., a young person's expressions of remorse and agreeing [or not] with the outcome, among other variables) could distinguish those young people who were and were not 'persistently reconvicted' during a 6-1/2 year follow up period. THE REAL OR THE TRUE STORY? Advocates want to tell a particular kind of story, the mythical true story of restorative justice. This story asks people to develop their 'caring' sides and to 'resist tyranny with compassion' (Braithwaite, 1999: 2). It suggests that amidst adversity, there is great potential 'for doing good' for self and others (paraphrasing Eckel, 1997; cited by Braithwaite, 1999: 2). It rewrites the history of justice practices by celebrating a return to pre-modern forms, and it re-colonises indigenous practices by identifying them as exemplars of restorative justice. The true story offers some hope, not only for a better way to do justice, but also for strengthening mechanisms of informal social control, and consequently, to minimise reliance on formal social control, the machinery and institutions of criminal justice. In order to sell the idea of restorative justice to a wide audience, advocates have painted a dichotomous, oppositional picture of different justice forms, with restorative justice trumping retributive justice as the superior one. There is a certain appeal to this framing of justice: it offers two choices, and it tells us which side is right. With this frame, who could possibly be on the side of retribution and retributive justice? Only the bad guys, of course. When we move from the metaphors and slogans to the hard work of establishing the 26 philosophical, legal, and organisational bases of this idea, and of documenting what actually occurs in these practices, the true story fails us. It lets us down because simple oppositional dualisms are inadequate in depicting criminal justice, even an ideal justice system, and no justice practice can be as extraordinary or successful most of the time, as the advocates would want us to think. The real story of restorative justice is a more qualified one. Empirical evidence of conferencing in Australia and New Zealand suggests that very high proportions of people find the process fair; on many measures of procedural justice, it succeeds. However, it is relatively more difficult for victims and offenders to find common ground and to hear each other's stories, or for offenders to give sincere apologies and victims to understand that apologies are sincere. There are limits on 'repairing the harm' for offenders and victims, in part because the idea is novel and unfamiliar for most ordinary citizens. For youthful lawbreakers, the limits also inhere in the salience of any legal process or adult exhortations to 'stay out of trouble', and the problems that adolescents may have in 'recognising the other', an empathetic orientation that is assumed to be central to a restorative process. For victims, the limits reside in the capacity to be generous to lawbreakers and to see lawbreakers as capable of change. A variety of observational and interview items from the SAJJ project suggests that a minority of conferences have the necessary raw material for restorativeness to occur. (One needs to be careful in generalising: the frequency of restorativeness would depend greatly on whether a jurisdiction uses conferences selectively or routinely and what kinds of cases are in the sample.) Overall, the real story of restorative justice has many positives and has much to commend, but the evidence is mixed. Conferencing, or any new justice practice, is not nirvana and ought not to be sold in those terms. In the political arena, telling the mythical true story of restorative justice may be an effective means of reforming parts of the justice system. It may inspire legislatures to pass 27 new laws and it may provide openings to experiment with alternative justice forms. All of this can be a good thing. Perhaps, in fact, the politics of selling justice ideas may require people to tell mythical true stories. The real story attends to the murk and constraints of justice organisations, of people's experiences as offenders and victims and their capacities and desires to 'repair the harm'. It reveals a picture that is less sharp-edged and more equivocal. My reading of the evidence is that face-to-face encounters between victims and offenders and their supporters is a practice worth maintaining, and perhaps enlarging, although we should not expect it to deliver strong stories of repair and goodwill most of the time. If we want to avoid the cycle of optimism and pessimism (Matthews, 1988) that so often attaches to any justice innovation, then we should be courageous and tell the real story of restorative justice. But, in telling the real story, there is some risk that a fledgling idea will meet a premature death. 28 References Abel, Richard L. (1982) 'The contradictions of informal justice', in R. L. Abel (ed.) The Politics of Informal Justice, vol. 1, pp. 267-320. New York: Academic Press. Ashworth, Andrew (1993) 'Some doubts about restorative justice', Criminal Law Forum 4: 277-99. Bargen, Jenny (1996) 'Kids, cops, courts, conferencing and children's rights: a note on perspectives', Australian Journal of Human Rights 2(2): 209-28. Bazemore, Gordon and Mara Schiff (eds.) (2001) Restorative Community Justice. Cincinnati: Anderson Publishing. Bazemore, Gordon and Lode Walgrave (1999) 'Restorative juvenile justice: in search of fundamentals and an outline for systemic reform', in G. Bazemore and L. Walgrave (eds.) Restorative Juvenile Justice: Repairing the Harm of Youth Crime, pp. 45-74. Monsey, NY: Criminal Justice Press. Blagg, Harry (1997) 'A just measure of shame? Aboriginal youth and conferencing in Australia', British Journal of Criminology 37(4): 481-501. Bottoms, Anthony E. (1998) 'Five puzzles in von Hirsch's theory of punishment', in A. Ashworth and M. Wasik (eds.) Fundamentals of Sentencing Theory: Essays in Honour of Andrew von Hirsch, pp. 53-100. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Braithwaite, John (1996) 'Restorative justice and a better future', Dorothy J. Killam Memorial Lecture, reprinted in Dalhousie Review 76(1): 9-32. [citation to lecture ms.] Braithwaite, John (1999) 'Restorative justice: assessing optimistic and pessimistic accounts', in M. Tonry (ed.) Crime and Justice: A Review of Research 25: 1-127. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Braithwaite, John and Kathleen Daly (1994) 'Masculinities, violence and communitarian control', in T. Newburn and E. A. Stanko (eds.) Just Boys Doing Business?, pp. 189- 29 213. New York: Routledge. Braithwaite, John and Phillip Pettit (1990) Not Just Deserts: A Republican Theory of Criminal Justice. New York: Oxford. Cain, Maureen (2000) 'Orientalism, occidentalism and the sociology of crime', British Journal of Criminology 40(2): 239-60. Consedine, Jim. (1995) Restorative Justice: Healing the Effects of Crime. Lyttelton, New Zealand: Ploughshares Publications. Cottingham, John (1979) 'Varieties of retribution', Philosophical Quarterly 29: 238-46. Crawford, Adam (1997) The Local Governance of Crime: Appeals to Community and Partnerships. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Crawford, Adam (2001) 'The prospects for restorative youth justice in England and Wales: a tale of two acts', in K. McEvoy and T. Newburn (eds.) Criminology and Conflict Resolution, pp. xx-xx. London: Macmillan. Crawford, Adam and Jo Goodey (eds.) (2000) Integrating a Victim Perspective within Criminal Justice. Aldershot: Ashgate/Dartmouth. Daly, Kathleen (1989) 'Criminal justice ideologies and practices in different voices: some feminist questions about justice', International Journal of the Sociology of Law 17(1): 1-18. Daly, Kathleen (1998) 'Restorative justice: moving past the caricatures', Paper presented to Seminar on Restorative Justice, Institute of Criminology, University of Sydney Law School, Sydney, April. Daly, Kathleen (2000a) 'Revisiting the relationship between retributive and restorative justice', in H. Strang and J. Braithwaite (eds.) Restorative Justice: From Philosophy to Practice, pp. 33-54. Aldershot: Ashgate/Dartmouth. Daly, Kathleen (2000b) 'Sexual assault and restorative justice', paper presented at Restorative 30 Justice and Family Violence Conference, Australian National University, Canberra, July. Daly, Kathleen (2001a) 'Conferencing in Australia and New Zealand: variations, research findings, and prospects', in A. Morris and G. Maxwell (eds.) Restorative Justice for Juveniles: Conferencing, Mediation and Circles, pp. 59-84. Oxford: Hart Publishing Ltd. Daly, Kathleen (2001b) South Australia Juvenile Justice (SAJJ) Research on Conferencing, Technical Report No. 2: Research Instruments in Year 2 (1999) and Background Notes. School of Criminology and Criminal Justice, Griffith University, Brisbane, Queensland. Daly, Kathleen and Hennessey Hayes (2001) 'Restorative justice and conferencing in Australia', Trends & Issues in Crime and Criminal Justice No. 186. Canberra: Australian Institute of Criminology. http://www.aic.gov.au/publications/tandi/tandi186.html> Daly, Kathleen and Russ Immarigeon (1998) 'The past, present, and future of restorative justice: some critical reflections', Contemporary Justice Review 1(1): 21-45. Daly, Kathleen, Michele Venables, Mary McKenna, Liz Mumford, and Jane Christie- Johnston (1998) South Australia Juvenile Justice (SAJJ) Research on Conferencing, Technical Report No. 1: Project Overview and Research Instruments (Year 1), School of Criminology and Criminal Justice, Griffith University, Brisbane, Queensland. Davis, Gwynn (1992) Making Amends: Mediation and Reparation in Criminal Justice. London: Routledge. Delgado, Richard (2000) 'Prosecuting violence: a colloquy on race, community, and justice', Stanford Law Review 52: 751-74. 31 Duff, R. Antony (1992) 'Alternatives to punishment -- or alternative punishments?', in W. Cragg (ed.) Retributivism and Its Critics, pp. 44-68. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner. Duff, R. Antony (1996) 'Penal communications: recent work in the philosophy of punishment', in M. Tonry (ed.) Crime and Justice: A Review of Research 20: 1-97. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Duff, R. Antony (2001) 'Restoration and retribution', Paper presented to Cambridge Seminar on Restorative Justice, Toronto, May. Eckel, M. (1997) 'A Buddhist approach to repentance' in A. Etzioni and D. Carney (eds) Repentance: A Comparative Perspective, pp. xx-xx. New York: Rowman & Littlefield. Engel, David (1993) 'Origin myths; narratives of authority, resistance, disability, and law', Law & Society Review 27(4): 785-826. Feeley, Malcolm and Jonathan Simon (1992) 'The new penology; notes on the emerging strategy of corrections and its implications' Criminology 30(4): 449-74. Findlay, Mark (2000) 'Decolonising restoration and justice in transitional cultures' in H. Strang and J. Braithwaite (eds.) Restorative Justice: Philosophy to Practice, pp. 185- 201. Aldershot: Ashgate/Dartmouth. Garland, David (1996) 'The limits of the sovereign state', British Journal of Criminology 36(4): 445-71. Gilligan, Carol (1982) In a Different Voice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Hampton, Jean (1992) 'Correcting harms versus righting wrongs: the goal of retribution', UCLA Law Review 39: 1659-1702. Harris, M. Kay (1987) 'Moving into the new millennium: toward a feminist vision of justice', The Prison Journal 67: 27-38. Hayes, Hennessey and Kathleen Daly (2001) 'Family conferencing in South Australia and re- 32 offending: preliminary results from the SAJJ project', Paper presented to Australian and New Zealand Society of Criminology Conference, Melbourne, February. to appear Heidensohn, Frances (1986) 'Models of justice: Portia or Persephone? Some thoughts on equality, fairness and gender in the field of criminal justice', International Journal of the Sociology of Law 14: 287-98. Hudson, Barbara (1998) 'Restorative justice: the challenge of sexual and racial violence', Journal of Law and Society 25(2): 237-56. Hudson, Joe, Allison. Morris, Gabrielle Maxwell, and Burt Galaway (eds.) (1996) Family Group Conferences: Perspectives on Policy and Practice. Monsey, NY: Criminal Justice Press. La Prairie, Carol (1999) 'Some reflections on new criminal justice policies in Canada: restorative justice, alternative measures and conditional sentences', Australian and New Zealand Journal of Criminology 32(2): 139-52 Levrant, Sharon, Francis T. Cullen, Betsy Fulton, and John F. Wozniak (1999) 'Reconsidering restorative justice: the corruption of benevolence revisited?', Crime & Delinquency 45(1): 3-27. Masters, Guy and David Smith (1998) 'Portia and Persephone revisited: thinking about feeling in criminal justice', Theoretical Criminology 2(1): 5-27. Matthews, Roger. (1988) 'Reassessing informal justice', in R. Matthews (ed.) Informal Justice?, pp. 1-24. Newbury Park, CA: Sage. Maxwell, Gabrielle and Allison Morris (1993) Family, Victims and Culture: Youth Justice in Zealand. Wellington: Social Policy Agency and the Institute of Criminology, Victoria University of Wellington. Maxwell, Gabrielle and Allison Morris (1996) 'Research on family group conferences with 33 young offenders in New Zealand', in J. Hudson et al. (eds.) Family Group Conferences: Perspectives on Policy & Practice, pp. 88-110. Monsey, NY: Willow Tree Press. McCold, Paul (1999/2000) Real Justice Forum, Issue 8: 3 (1999), which summarises the venn diagram. His paper and responses are to appear in Contemporary Justice Review (2000), Vol. 3(4). Morris, Allison and Gabrielle Maxwell (2001) (eds.) Restorative Justice for Juveniles: Conferencing, Mediation and Circles. Oxford: Hart Publishing Ltd. Mead, George Herbert (1917-18) 'The psychology of punitive justice', The American Journal of Sociology 23: 577-602 [reprinted in The Sociology of Punishment, Dario Melossi (ed.)]. O'Malley, Pat (1999) 'Volatile and contradictory punishment', Theoretical Criminology 3(2): 175-96. Pavlich, George C. (1996) Justice Fragmented: Mediating Community Disputes under Postmodern Conditions. New York: Routledge. Pratt, John (2000) 'The return of the wheelbarrow men; or, the arrival of postmodern penality?', British Journal of Criminology 40: 127-45. Shearing, Clifford (2001) 'Punishment and the changing face of the governance', Punishment & Society 3(2): 230-20. Strang, Heather, Lawrence W. Sherman, Geoffrey C. Barnes, and John Braithwaite (1999) Experiments in Restorative Policing: A Progress Report to the National Police Research Unit on the Canberra Reintegrative Shaming Experiments (RISE). Canberra: Australian National University. 34 Snider, Laureen (1998) 'Toward safer societies: punishment, masculinities and violence against women', British Journal of Criminology 38(1): 1-39. Tonry, Michael (1999) 'Rethinking unthinkable punishment policies in America', UCLA Law Review 46(4): 1751-91. Umbreit, Mark (1994) Victim Meets Offender: The Impact of Restorative Justice and Mediation. Monsey, NY: Criminal Justice Press. Van Ness, Daniel (1993) 'New wine and old wineskins: four challenges of restorative justice', Criminal Law Forum 4: 251-76. Van Ness, Daniel and Karen Strong (1997) Restoring Justice. Cincinnati: Anderson Publishing. Walgrave, Lode (1995) 'Restorative justice for juveniles: just a technique or a fully fledged alternative?', The Howard Journal 34: 228-49. Walgrave, Lode and Ivo Aertsen (1996) 'Reintegrative shaming and restorative justice: interchangeable, complementary or different?', European Journal on Criminal Policy and Research 4: 67-85. Weitekamp, Elmar (1999) 'The history of restorative justice', in G. Bazemore and L. Walgrave (eds.) Restorative Juvenile Justice: Repairing the Harm of Youth Crime, pp. xx-xx. Monsey, NY: Criminal Justice Press. Wright, Martin (1991) Justice for Victims and Offenders. Philadelphia: Open University Press. Zedner, Lucia (1994) 'Reparation and retribution: are they reconcilable?', Modern Law Review 57: 228-50. Zehr, Howard. (1995) 'Justice paradigm shift? Values and vision in the reform process', Mediation Quarterly 12(3): 207-16. 35 Notes i Indicative examples of advocates are Bazemore and Walgrave (1999), Braithwaite (1999), Consedine (1995), Van Ness and Strong (1997), Umbreit (1994), and Zehr (1995). Among the skeptics/critics are Ashworth (1993), Blagg (1997), Delgado (2000), Hudson (1998), Levrant et al. (1999), and Pavlich (1996). Because the modern idea of restorative justice is new, publications reporting research are few. Among them are contributors in collections edited by Bazemore and Schiff (2001), Crawford and Goodey (2000), Hudson et al. (1996), and Morris and Maxwell (2001). ii Conferences are meetings where an admitted offender(s), his/her supporters, a victim(s), his/her supporters, and relevant other people come together to discuss the offence, its impact, and what sanction (or reparation) is appropriate. The conference, which is run by a coordinator and attended by a police officer, is typically used as diversion from court prosecution, but it may also be used to provide pre-sentencing advice to judges and magistrates. Police-run diversionary conferencing is highly atypical of Australian and New Zealand conferencing, whereas it is more typical in UK and North American practices. See Bargen (1996), Daly and Hayes (2001), and Hudson et al. (1996) for overviews of jurisdiction variation in Australia and New Zealand. iii McCold's proposal is discussed and debated in Contemporary Justice Review (2000); my reference is to his initial article in Real Justice Forum (1999). iv Drawing from Cottingham's (1979) analysis of retribution's many meanings, restorative justice advocates tend to use retributivism to mean 'repayment' (to which they add a punitive kick) whereas desert theorists, such as von Hirsch, use retributivism to mean 'deserved' and would argue for decoupling retribution from punitiveness. 36 v It is important to emphasise that 'new justice' practices have not been applied to the fact-finding stage of the criminal process; they are used almost exclusively for the penalty phase. Some comparative claims about restorative justice practices (e.g., they are not adversarial when retributive justice is) are misleading in that restorative justice attends only to the penalty phase when negotiation is possible. No one has yet sketched a restorative justice process for those who do not admit to an offence. vi I became aware of the term 'new justice' from LaPrairie's (1999) analysis of developments in Canada. She defines 'new justice' initiatives as representing a 'shift away from a justice discourse of punitiveness and punishment toward one of reconciliation, healing, repair, atonement, and reintegration' (p. 147), and she sees such developments as part of a new emphasis on 'community' and 'partnership' as analysed by Crawford (1997). vii Restorative justice advocates speak of the harm not of the crime, and in doing so, they elide a crucial distinction between a civil and criminal harm, the latter involving both a harm and a wrong (Duff, 2001). viii In response to this point, one reader said there had to be some way to theorise varied justice forms (both in an empirical and normative sense), and thus, the 'disappointment' I speak of reflects a disenchantment with the theoretical enterprise to adequately reflect particularity and variation in the empirical social world. This is a longstanding problem in the sociological field. What troubles me is the construction of theoretical terms in the justice field, which use dualisms in adversarial and oppositional relation to one another. ix There are other, more sophisticated, analyses of the ethics of care and its applicability to criminal justice. For example, Snider (1998) argues that we need to learn more about 'activities of caring ... or the implications of such an orientation, compared to those central to punishing' (pp. 27-28). 37 x The major research studies in the region are Maxwell and Morris (1993) for New Zealand, Strang et al. (1999) for the ACT and the RISE project, and the results reported here for the SAJJ project in South Australia. See Daly (2001a) for a review of these and other studies. Space limitations preclude a review of the methods of each study; rather, general findings are summarised. xi It is important to distinguish jurisdictions like South Australia, New South Wales, and New Zealand, where conferences are used routinely from other jurisdictions (like Victoria and Queensland), where conferences are used selectively and in a relatively few number of cases. When conferences are used routinely, we should not expect to see 'restorativeness' emerging most of the time. xii Space limitations preclude a review of the definitions and methods used in the re-offending studies; rather general findings are summarised. work_5fxjqcvdcvhhvpvfn3gf4kwdj4 ---- Science Magazine 1072 EDITED BY KRISTEN MUELLER AND JAKE YESTON EDITORS’CHOICE C R E D IT S ( T O P T O B O T T O M ): S O E Z E Y A T U N /R T R /N E W S C O M ; F O T O S E A R C H 26 AUGUST 2011 VOL 333 SCIENCE www.sciencemag.org ing data from fi ve national surveys conducted between 1975 and 2007, Siikamäki attempted to assess the value of one aspect of state parks: recreation. About a third of the time people cur- rently spend on nature recreation in the United States is accounted for in state parks. Although use of state parks has declined over the time pe- riod covered in the surveys, the cost of running the parks remains easily outdistanced by the rec- reation value derived from the parks. Following the conventional approach of valuing recreation time at one-third of paid wage time, the value of nature recreation in state parks reaches about $14 billion annually, whereas annual opera- tion costs total about $2.3 billion. Thus, these sometimes unassuming parks build a network that delivers ecosystem and economic value, as well as just giving us a nice day. — PJH Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 108, 10.1073/ pnas.1108688108 (2011). C H E M I S T R Y Stuffi ng Your Struts The potential for using metal-organic frame- works (MOFs) as catalysts is often frustrated by a fundamental tradeoff. The synthetic routes for S O C I O L O G Y Not Contagious After All? Studies of social infl uences on behavior have led to the idea that a range of characteristics from loneliness to obesity might be contagious. A signifi cant problem for the fi eld has been to distinguish effects due to similarities between people (homophily) from social infl uence. One strategy for doing this has been to look at changes that occur over time. However, such studies have been the subject of consider- able debate, and Noel and Nyhan now add a cautionary note. Their analyses of a model used in past social contagion studies suggest that previous investigations have not fully controlled for the possibility that friendship formation and termination are dynamic processes, and friend- ships between people who are more similar may tend to be more stable over time. Or to put it in Facebook terms, friendships that are between people who are less similar may be less stable, and therefore may result in “unfriending.” Homophily might thus be having a larger effect than appreciated, and under certain conditions could account for most of the contagion effects observed. They conclude that this unfriending problem renders a determination of causality much more complicated in longitudinal social network data. — BJ Soc. Networks 33, 211 (2011). P O L I C Y The Value of State Parks State parks in the United States can be a refuge for wildlife, a reservoir of plant diversity, or a source of untamed water. They are also a popular destination for recreation. But recent economic belt-tightening means that budgets for state parks are going under the knife. By analyz- G E O P H Y S I C S To Catch a Quake Large earthquakes leave affected populations disoriented and emergency responders scrambling. Having fast, reliable estimates of the location and magnitude of the mainshock and its aftershocks is vital to an effective rapid response plan. In developing countries with the potential for large earthquakes, installing and maintaining seismic networks to collect such data can be expensive. The Quake-Catcher Network is a volunteer-based seismic network that employs personal computers as low-cost seismic sta- tions by sending seismic data collected with a small USB accelerometer through the user’s Internet connection. Although this network had yet to be installed in Chile before the 2010 M 8.8 Maule earthquake, volunteers rapidly installed nearly 100 accelerometers within weeks in and around the mainshock area, including stations set up in local government build- ings, health stations, and homes. Chung et al. describe the network’s ability to accurately collect and discriminate aftershock data and shaking intensity estimates—most within 30 s of an individual event. Improve- ments in accelerometer technology and data processing will probably improve data quality to the point that future networks of hundreds or thousands of stations installed in high-seismicity regions will aid fi rst responders in determining where most help is needed after a large earth- quake strikes. — NW Seismol. Res. Lett. 82, 526 (2011). Published by AAAS o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 h ttp ://scie n ce .scie n ce m a g .o rg / D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://science.sciencemag.org/ EDITORS’CHOICE www.sciencemag.org SCIENCE VOL 333 26 AUGUST 2011 making MOFs tend to saturate all of the coor- dination sites of metals, even ones contained within the linkers or struts, but catalysis by met- als is usually enabled by the presence of unsatu- rated sites. Shultz et al. developed a strategy that addresses this dilemma for metallosalen struts to use as catalysts within MOFs. Although Mn(salen) can be incorporated into MOFs for asymmetric epoxidations, other metals, such as Co(salen) for asymmetric ring opening, are unsaturated and do not form MOFs directly. The authors describe how Mn(salen) MOFs (in which zinc ions link the struts in a paddlewheel arrangement) can be demetalated with H2O2 and replaced isostructurally with a wide variety of dicationic transition-metal ions, including Co, Cr, Cu, Zn, and reduced Mn (which recovered its catalytic activity after reoxidation). — PDS J. Am. Chem. Soc. 133, 10.1021/ ja204820d (2011). C E L L B I O L O G Y Small Changes Have Big Consequences Protein folding and the maintenance of a healthy proteome often involve molecular chap- erones of the heat shock protein 70 (Hsp70) family. The basis of functional distinctions of highly homologous and functionally redundant Hsp70s is unknown. Nearly identical yeast cytosolic Hsp70s, Ssa1p and Ssa2p, function dif- ferently in the propagation of yeast prions and in a vacuole-import and protein-degradation pathway involved in regulating levels of gluco- neogenesis enzymes. By swapping amino acids, Sharma and Masison show that a single amino acid difference in the nucleotide-binding regula- tory domain of the Ssa proteins is the basis for the functional distinction in both processes. It seems that this small structural difference affects regulation of Hsp70 by cofactors rather than by altering intrinsic Hsp70 activity. Thus, subtle changes in Hsp70 structure may have evolved to confer functional specifi city without affecting overall Hsp70 function. — SMH Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 10.1073/ pnas.1107421108 (2011). P O L I C Y Basic Implications In 1980, the United States adopted the Bayh- Dole Act, which allowed researchers to retain intellectual property rights to federally funded research, as a way to encourage the development of technologies that might otherwise languish in labs. Since then, the number of university technology transfer offi ces has boomed, along with patent applications and licensing income. Despite this apparent success, some argue that the act has co-opted universities and undermined the overall scientifi c and economic enterprise, with long-term academic pursuit of knowledge through basic research abandoned in favor of nearer-term profi ts. Thursby and Thursby exam- ined whether basic research has indeed suffered relative to applied research since Bayh-Dole. They analyzed data on thousands of science and engineering faculty from eight major U.S. research universities spanning the years 1983 to 1999. The “basicness” of faculty research was explored via publication analysis, on the reasoning that “basic” journals are cited more heavily by “applied” journals than vice versa. They assessed faculty interest in commercial- izing research by tracking the history of formally disclosing potential inventions. Their model also accounted for research funding, age, tenure, and other infl uences. They found no evidence that interest in commercialization detracted from basic research, and in fact saw that basic research effort increased in light of the incentive of potential commercialization profi ts. — BW Res. Policy 40, 1077 (2011). P S Y C H O L O G Y Human Justice Are decisions made by judges, which are sup- posed to be made on the basis of facts and legal reasoning, also infl uenced by outside variables such as ethnicity or even how recently the judge had a meal? Shayo and Zussman examined 1750 small claims court rulings handed down by more than 100 judges in Israel from 2000 to 2004; these court cases were fender-bender traffi c accidents in which the plaintiff and defen- dant were of different ethnicities. They found a pattern of ingroup bias: Jewish judges favored Jewish plaintiffs, and Arab judges favored Arab plaintiffs. By considering the times and loca- tions of civilian fatalities during this period, the authors decompose these decisions into half that were arguably ethnicity-neutral and a more biased half associated with spatial-temporal proximity to terrorism, highlighting that a person’s ability to favor their own social group may affect seemingly rational judgments. Danziger et al. analyzed 1100 parole board decisions made by eight judges in Israel in a 10-month period. They document a bias toward retaining the status quo (that is, denying parole) in successive cases adjudicated in a single day. This tendency was eliminated after each of two food breaks, suggesting that cognitive balance can be restored after resource depletion. — GJC Q. J. Econ. 126, 10.1093/qje/qjr022 (2011); Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 108, 6889 (2011). 17050 Montebello Road Cupertino, California 95014 Email: AAASInfo@betchartexpeditions.com www.betchartexpeditions.com For a detailed brochure, please call (800) 252-4910 All prices are per person twin share + air Costa Rica & Nicaragua On board Star Flyer Nov. 27–Dec. 4, 2011 Discover San Juan del Sur and Lago Nicaragua (the Atlantic- Pacific crossing before the Panama Canal) and national parks along the coast of Costa Rica. Discover birds, turtles, sloths and snorkel in pristine santuaries. From $2,995 + air Antarctica on Sale! On board M/V Plancius Dec. 30, 2011–Jan. 11, 2012 Explore the greatest frontier on earth, a magnificent wilderness with a profusion of penguins, whales, and seals. See spectacular mountains&glacierswhich lunge to the sea. Explore by zodiac, foot & kayak. Simply breathtaking! From $5,995 quad + air BETCHART EXPEDITIONS Inc. AAAS is here – bringing educational infrastructure to the developing world. AAAS is helping the Rwandan government rebuild its educational infrastructure. By providing materials such as the Project 2061 Atlas of Science Literacy, lesson plans from Science NetLinks, and access to Science digital libraries, AAAS is helping the people of Rwanda work toward a future built around science and technology. If you’re not yet a AAAS member, join us. Together we can make a difference. To learn more, visit aaas.org/plusyou/rwanda Published by AAAS o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 h ttp ://scie n ce .scie n ce m a g .o rg / D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://science.sciencemag.org/ Human Justice Gilbert Chin DOI: 10.1126/science.333.6046.1073-c (6046), 1073.333Science ARTICLE TOOLS http://science.sciencemag.org/content/333/6046/1073.3 CONTENT RELATED file:/content/sci/333/6046/twil.full PERMISSIONS http://www.sciencemag.org/help/reprints-and-permissions Terms of ServiceUse of this article is subject to the is a registered trademark of AAAS.ScienceScience, 1200 New York Avenue NW, Washington, DC 20005. The title (print ISSN 0036-8075; online ISSN 1095-9203) is published by the American Association for the Advancement ofScience Copyright © 2011, American Association for the Advancement of Science o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 h ttp ://scie n ce .scie n ce m a g .o rg / D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://science.sciencemag.org/content/333/6046/1073.3 http://www.sciencemag.org/help/reprints-and-permissions http://www.sciencemag.org/about/terms-service http://science.sciencemag.org/ work_5hwszkygcnerhoi7zq5sn7rjdy ---- BRITISH MEDICAL JOURNAL VOLUME 291 20 JULY 1985 201~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~ Philosophical Medical Ethics Justice and medical ethics RAANAN GILLON Some argue that medical ethics should have no truck with justice in the sense of fair adjudication between competing claims. Especially in the context of distributing scarce medical resources they take the view that the proper role of doctors is the Hippocratic one of doing the best they can for each patient. Their patients suffer when doctors start to temper this obligation with any conflicting con- siderations of fairness or justice.' I pointed out in my article on beneficence that if doctors chose not to concern themselves with justice in medical practice then inevit- ably others would (and should) so concern themselves. In any case the idea that doctors can somehow legitimately evade any need to concern themselves with justice is hardly tenable given that in the course of their practice they are often confronted with conflicting claims on their resources, even from their own patients. The doctor who stays in theatre to finish a long and difficult operation and consequently misses an outpatient clinic is probably relying- implicitly or explicitly-on some sort of theory of justice whereby he can fairly decide to override his obligation to his outpatients in favour of his obligation to the patient on the table. So is the general practitioner who spends 30 minutes with the bereaved mother and only five with the lonely old lady who has a sore throat. Nor do distributive concerns-the proper allocation of benefits and burdens-exhaust the relevance of justice to medical ethics. In the Arthur case the prosecution was concerned that those who break the law should be punished-an aspect of reparative, retributive, or corrective justice. Forensic psychiatrists, who concern themselves with the sanity or "competence" of clients charged with offences, are concerned with responsibility in the context of reparative justice. The Declaration of Tokyo's absolute prohibition of medical involvement in torture affirms a concept of justice based on rights that forbids certain things to be done to other people even if doing them may be of great social benefit. The General Medical Council, as a quasi court of law, is concerned with specifically legal aspects of justice. Even the selection of medical students or appointment of new medical colleagues concerns justice. So the idea that justice is a moral issue that doctors can properly ignore is clearly mistaken. Aristotle's principle of justice Justice has always been one of the central concerns of philoso- phers, and indeed Aristotle's formal principle of justice is still widely accepted. Aristotle, somewhat hampered by the fact that the Greek word for justice was cognate with the Greek word for equality, was at pains to reject the claims of the democratic factions of Athens, who argued that justice meant equal shares for all (well, for all freemen). In a sophisticated treatment Aristotle distinguished between justice as another term for overall goodness or "complete virtue" and justice in a narrower sense, concerning equality of treatment. Such equality could not be sensibly understood as mere equal division of whatever benefit or burden was being considered, for "the origin of complaints and quarrels [is] when either equals have and are awarded unequal shares, or unequals equal shares."' Instead, argued Aristotle, the equality of justice had to be understood as meaning fair or proportionate treatment. He pointed out that in the latter sense justice was a relative term, in terms of relations both between people and for any one person between what he was owed and what he deserved. Those who deserved the same were owed the same, and in that sense justice required equality of treatment. Those, however, who deserved more were owed more, while those who deserved less were owed less. In both cases, as what they were owed was in strict proportion to their deserts, once again justice required people to be treated equally. The formal principle of justice or equality attributed to Aristotle is, therefore, that equals should be treated equally and unequals unequally in proportion to the relevant inequalities.6 The reason that Aristotle's formal principle remains so widely accepted is, of course, that it has little substantive content. It requires an equality of consideration (for an excellent contemporary analysis of the concept of equality see Bernard Williams's paper The idea ofequality)7; fairness in the sense that conflicts are to be settled by mutually agreed principles of justice (for an account of fairness and fairplay see John Rawls's paper 7ustice as fairness)8; and impartiality in the sense that inequalities9 of treatment cannot be arbitrary-based on mere opinion, preference, or partiality-but must be justified on the basis of, and in proportion to, relevant inequalities9 (for a useful analysis of the concept of moral relevance see R M Hare's paper Relevance'°). These concepts of fairness and impartiality, however, are also formal in that they do not specify the content of the "relevant inequalities" or the agreed principles. Different theories of justice can and do flesh out differently Aristotle's formal principle of justice with its demands for equal consideration, fairness, and impartiality. My somewhat contentious view is that these differences usually arise because priority is given to different moral principles as the basis for assessing people's just deserts. From the wide range of existing theories of justice five important types can be distinguished in this way. Libertarian theories Libertarian theories of justice emphasise that people should be accorded maximal respect for their personal liberty. Such theories usually start from a Lockean social contract designed to protect people's personal rights"-but, unlike Locke's theory, they often emphasise only the last of his natural rights to life, health, liberty, and possessions. The result is what might be called economic libertarianism, stemming from the theories of Adam Smith'2 via those of F A Hayek'3 (and in theory of the present governments of Mrs Thatcher and President Reagan) to that of the contemporary American philosopher Robert Nozik, who has purged these theories of any traces of utilitarian welfare maximising contaminants. Although claiming to base his theory on a defence of Lockean Imperial College of Science and Technology, London SW7 INA RAANAN GILLON, MB, MRCP, director, Imperial College health service, editor, Journal ofMedical Ethics, and associate director, Institute of Medical Ethics BRITISH MEDICAL JOURNAL VOLUME 291 20 JULY 1985 201 o n 5 A p ril 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://w w w .b m j.co m / B r M e d J (C lin R e s E d ): first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /b m j.2 9 1 .6 4 8 9 .2 0 1 o n 2 0 Ju ly 1 9 8 5 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://www.bmj.com/ 202 BRITISH MEDICAL JOURNAL VOLUME 291 20 JULY 1985 natural rights, Nozik concentrates on only two of those rights; the right to life-that is, not to be unjustly killed-and the right to have possessions. Nozik argues that provided people acquire and transfer their "holdings" without violating others' rights no one is entitled to take them away. On that basis he argues that any taxation, beyond what is necessary to maintain the "minimal state" required to protect life and holdings, "is on a par with forced labour."'4 Nozik's arguments have provoked vigorous philosophical response.'5 One of the criticisms is that if the whole spectrum of Lockean rights allegedly of concern to Nozik is to be protected his conclusions against taxation to benefit the poor and sick and otherwise disadvantaged are unsupported by his theory. Utilitarian theories Utilitarian theories emphasise that people deserve to have their welfare maximised. The danger of such theories is that in their simplistic versions they give too little weight to Lockean personal rights, which they are prepared to override whenever to do so is likely to maximise overall welfare. As I have indicated in my articles on utilitarianism and autonomy sophisticated utilitarian theories from Mill onwards have shown awareness of these dangers and have incorporated moral concern for personal liberty (in the sense of autonomy) as a required condition of maximisation of welfare. Professor RM Hare's form ofutilitarianism sees the formal principle of justice as "nothing but a restatement of the requirement that moral principles be universalisable"-a principle that according to Hare is manifested in Bentham's principle that everybody counts for one and nobody for more than one. 6 Marxist theories Marxist theories of justice emphasise that people deserve to have their needs met; people's "deserts" are thus in direct proportion to their needs and Aristotle's formal principle of justice can be met by making needs the relevant inequality. Apart from conceptual problems-What are needs?-Marxist moral theory faces objec- tiJO\ similar to those levelled at simplistic utilitarianism-notably, that other moral concerns, particularly respect for individual autonomy, may be overriden in order to satisfy human needs. The Marxist corollary of "to each according to his needs" is "from each according to his ability," and the operation of this rule, according to Lenin, results in "actual equality."' It is a rule that, again in its simplistic versions, brooks no rejection. ("The communists disdain to conceal their views and aims. They openly declare that their ends can be attained only by the forcible overthrow of all existing conditions."')' Once again we must distinguish between simplistic and sophisti- cated versions, for sophisticated Marxists are undoubtedly aware of the dangers of inadequate concern for individual autonomy or freedom,'9-" and Marx himself sees a community of autonomous people living together in peace, harmony, and true consciousness as the utopian "objective" of the inexorable march of history. Rawls's theory of justice A highly infloiential attempt to blend utilitarian theories and those theories of justice that respect autonomy-and indeed to incor- porate the element of need of Marxist theories-is Professor John Rawls's theory of justice.22 2 As previously indicated, he argues that people coming together to work out a theory of justice for their society, and rendered impartial by the device of a "veil of ignorance" whereby they do not know what role they are to have in that society, would choose a system of justice whose first principle was that people should have the maximal liberty compatible with the same degree of liberty for everyone and whose second principle was that deliberate inequalities were unjust unless they worked to the advantage of the least well off. Reward for merit Finally, the claim that justice is essentially a matter of reward for individual merit-the view, for instance, of W D Ross24-remains plausible in at least some circumstances. For example, all com- petitions based on skill implicitly assume a principle of justice based on merit, including competitions to enter medical schools or obtain medical posts. Athletics competitions presuppose that "the best man (or woman) wins." The structure of wages in a capitalist society, whereby skilled work is rewarded more highly than unskilled work, again presupposes both that skills confer merit and that merit should be rewarded. On the other hand, can all distribution of benefits and burdens be fairly or justly determined on the basis of merit and demerit? In particular, there is no merit in being ill: should medical resources be allocated according to merit rather than illness? So varied and so complex are theories of justice that more than with the other moral principles it would be hopeless even to suggest a generally acceptable substantive position. Instead it seems more useful to acknowledge that people's theories of justice are likely to continue to differ, I suspect largely on the basis of the relative weights they assign to the moral principles I have already outlined -that is, respect for autonomy, beneficence, and non-maleficence. I shall next look at allocation of scarce medical resources in the context of these various substantive theories of justice and in the light of Aristotle's formal principle of justice, which is implicitly accepted by them all. References I.csitskv NG. 'lThe doctor's master. AN Engl.7 Aled 1984;31 1:1573-5. 2 Kempcrman CJF. Clinical decisions. Lancet 1982;ii: 1222. 3 I'arsons V, Lock P. Triage anid the patient with renal failure. 7 Med Ethics 1980;6:173-6. 4 Macara S, reported by Edwards S. No room for triage in NHS. Medical Newvs 1983; 15-22 Dccember:27. 5 Aristotle. Nicomacheatt ethics. 1131a:22-5. 6 Aristotle. Nicomtacheatt ethics, Book 5 and Politics, Book 3, Chapter 9. 7 Williams B. 'The idea of equality. In: Williams B, ed. Problems of the self: Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1976:230-49. 8 Rawls J. Jtistice as fairness. 7he Philosophical Review 1958;67:164-94. 9 Benn S. Justice. In: Edwards 1', ed. The encyclopedia of'philosophy. New York, London: Collier Macmillan, 1967:298-302. 10 Hare RM. Relevance. In: Goldman Al, Kim J, eds. V'alues and morals. Dordrecht: Reidel, 1978:73-90. 11 Locke J. Second treatise on government. 1690. Chapter 2; section 6. 12 Smith A. 7'he wvealth of nations. 1776. 13 Hayek F. Ittdividualism and economic order. Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1948. 14 Nozik R. Anarchv, state, and utopia. Oxford: Blackwell, 1974:169. 15 Plaul J, ed. Reading Nozik. Oxford: Blackwell, 1981. 16 Hare RM. Moral thiniting: its levels, method atnd point. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1981:147-68. 17 Lenin VI. The state and revolution. Moscow: Progress l'ublishers, 1972:91. 18 Marx K, Engels F. Manifesto of the Communist Party. In: Hobsbawm EJ, ed.The age oJ revolutiott. London: Cardinal/Sphere, 1973:285. 19 Marcuse H. Freedom and the historical imperative. In: Marcuse H, ed. Studies in critical philosophv. London: Verso/NLB, 1972. 20 Kamenka E. Marxism and ethics. London: Macmillan, 1969. 21 Bottomore '', ed. A dictionarv oJ Marxist thought. Oxford: Blackwell, 1985. 22 Rawls J. A theory ofjustice. Oxford: Oxford Univesity Press, 1976. 23 Daniels N, ed. Reading Rasvls. Oxford: Blackwell, 1975. 24 Ross WD. The right and the good. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1930:26-7. Bibliography Bcauchamp 'I'L. Justice. In: Beauchamp rL, ed. Philosophical ethics: an introduction to moral philosopkv. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1982:219-58. President's Commission for the study of ethical problems in medicine. Securing access to health care. Washington: US Government Printing Office, 1983. Campbell AV. Medici,ne, health and justice-the problent of pnronrties. Edinburgh: Churchill Living- stone, 1978. Correction Outbreak of poliomyelitis in Finland In the fourth paragraph of the CDSC Report "Outbreak of poliomyelitis in Finland" (6 July, p 41) line 7 (p 42) should have read "regular Salk type trivalent poliovirus vaccine for all children under the age of 18 years." The total number of cases was larger than six. The full details of the outbreak will be published by the Finnish investigators later. We apologise for this error. o n 5 A p ril 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://w w w .b m j.co m / B r M e d J (C lin R e s E d ): first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /b m j.2 9 1 .6 4 8 9 .2 0 1 o n 2 0 Ju ly 1 9 8 5 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://www.bmj.com/ work_5jejxielurg47lblqdagudvsii ---- Food justice for all?: searching for the ‘justice multiple’ in UK food movements Vol.:(0123456789)1 3 Agriculture and Human Values (2021) 38:43–58 https://doi.org/10.1007/s10460-020-10142-5 Food justice for all?: searching for the ‘justice multiple’ in UK food movements Helen Coulson1  · Paul Milbourne1 Accepted: 12 August 2020 / Published online: 19 August 2020 © The Author(s) 2020 Abstract In this paper, we examine diverse political philosophical conceptualisations of justice and interrogate how these contested understandings are drawn upon in the burgeoning food justice scholarship. We suggest that three interconnected dimensions of justice—plurality, the spatial–temporal and the more-than-human—deserve further analytical attention and propose the notion of the ‘justice multiple’ to bring together a multiplicity of framings and situated practices of (food) justice. Given the lack of critical engagement food justice has received as both a concept and social movement in the context of the United Kingdom (UK), we draw upon empirical research with practitioners and activists involved with heterogenous food movements working at the local, regional and national level and apply the justice multiple concept to the interview data. We highlight the diverse ways that justice is discussed in terms of access, fairness, empowerment, rights and dignity that reflect established organisational discursive framings and the fragmented nature of food system advocacy and activism. Based on this insight, we argue that a plurivocal, relational conceptualisation of socioecological justice can help enhance the multiple politics of food justice, pluralise UK food movement praxis and nurture avenues for broader coalition-building across the food system. Keyword Food justice · Food movements · Justice · Justice theories · Right to food Abbreviations GMO Genetically Modified Organisms NGO Non-Governmental Organisation UK United Kingdom US United States Introduction The notion of food justice has increasingly been evoked by various civil society groups as a powerful mobilising con- cept in the United Kingdom (UK) context. This has primar- ily occurred as a direct consequence of the ongoing impacts of austerity and welfare reform which has witnessed the proliferation of hunger and poverty (Just Fair 2014; O’Hara 2014; Nourish Scotland and the Poverty Truth Commission 2018; End Hunger UK 2019; MacLeod 2019; Raj 2019). However, despite this recent intensification of the politici- sation of food-related inequities, we argue that ‘justice’— as a contested idea and practice—in food justice deserves far greater critical scholarly and activist attention by those involved with heterogenous UK food movements.1 Indeed, the ways in which food justice is deployed in the UK have evaded critical scrutiny (however, see Tornaghi 2016; Kneafsey et al. 2017; Herman and Goodman 2018; Mama D and Anderson 2018), particularly the complex translation politics of drawing upon a concept that has deep situated roots in environmental and social justice movements of the United States (US). This raises the potential issue of misla- belling food-related activities that neglect addressing class and racial injustice (Slocum 2018) or stretching the concept to empty signifier status when applied to different contexts (Heynen et al. 2012), which can ultimately depoliticise activ- ism and stymie marginalised voices. While justice is open to multiple interpretations, food jus- tice activism in the US has placed racial equity and racial justice (rooted in civil rights and environmental justice * Helen Coulson coulsonh1@cardiff.ac.uk Paul Milbourne milbournep@cardiff.ac.uk 1 School of Geography and Planning, Cardiff University, Glamorgan Building, King Edward VII Avenue, Cardiff, Wales CF10 3WA, UK 1 The phrase ‘food movement’ is utilised to designate the multiplic- ity of activists, practitioners, alternative food initiatives and coalition networks working to address diverse food system issues such as envi- ronmental sustainability and food (in)security. http://orcid.org/0000-0002-3082-2377 http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1007/s10460-020-10142-5&domain=pdf 44 H. Coulson, P. Milbourne 1 3 struggles) at the heart of its praxis (Alkon and Norgaard 2009; Alkon and Agyeman 2011; Myers and Sbicca 2015; Reynolds and Cohen 2016; Penniman 2018). Critical race theory has been central in grounding ideas of (abstract) jus- tice through an intersectional analysis (of class, race, gender, (dis)ability and sexuality) that contextualises processes of domination and resistance within a broader socio-histori- cal framework (Alkon and Agyeman 2011; Agyeman and McEntee 2014; Cadieux and Slocum 2015; Penniman 2018). Food justice scholar-activists/activist-scholars therefore start from the position of a normative commitment to justice that emphasises the necessity of reconfiguring socioecological relations and enacting structural change, while acknowledg- ing that how justice is articulated and utilised will reflect place-based grounded concerns (Cadieux and Slocum 2015) often occupying a spectrum ranging from ‘progressive’ to ‘radical’ approaches (Holt-Giménez and Shattuck 2011). The ongoing tensions between the emancipatory potential of food justice activism and neoliberal constraints have been widely documented, particularly the tendency of food move- ments to prioritise entrepreneurial, market-centric strategies for social change (Alkon 2014). Furthermore, the over-reli- ance on volunteerism, self-exploitation and grant funding, and the reproduction of (race, class and gender) privilege within community groups and food justice organisations have been extensively critiqued (see, for example, Guthman 2008; Alkon and Mares 2012; McClintock 2014; Montalvo 2015; Broad 2016). In the UK, there is a long and vibrant history of social justice activism led by marginalised groups tackling inequal- ity, poverty and injustice, in which food has often played an important role (Sutton 2016). While actually existing food movements are multifaceted, fluid and fragmented with diverse and frequently contrasting priorities, contemporary UK food-related issues have been approached through two broad avenues. First, those engaging with food politics have gravitated towards the (re)connections between food produc- tion and consumption through various food ‘qualities’ (such as local, slow and organic) often related predominately to health and environmental sustainability objectives (Kneaf- sey et al. 2017). Consequently, mainstream environmentally- orientated food activism in the UK has tended to be domi- nated by white, middle-class consumers concentrating on the development of local food systems and individualised consumptive logics of social change that reinforce social privilege and fail to address the underlying structural causes of food injustice (Paddock 2016). Second, issues of food poverty since the 2007–8 finan- cial crisis have been framed through a predominately social welfare lens, focusing on food insecurity (Dowler and Lam- bie-Mumford 2015) and the contested spaces of food banks (Williams et al. 2016). Growing attention has been placed on the underlying issues driving people towards food charity (cf. Poppendieck 1998; Caraher and Furey 2018; MacLeod 2019), principally income inequality, the rising cost of liv- ing and punitive welfare restructuring (which has reduced social security entitlements and intensified conditionality) under the “alchemy of austerity” (Clarke and Newman 2012, p. 300). The cross-cutting nature of food and the stark ‘vis- ibility’ of food poverty in contemporary UK society has acted as a catalyst for anti-hunger activism to increasingly frame its advocacy through a (rights-based) social justice, rather than charity, framework (End Hunger UK 2019). However, despite calls to develop integrated socioecological approaches to food system problems (Holt-Giménez 2011), in practice tensions persist between anti-hunger activism (focusing primarily on social justice concerns) and ‘alter- native’ food movement practices (which prioritise environ- mental sustainability issues), thus impeding the possibilities of nurturing food justice for all. The aim of this paper is to examine through an explicit pluralised justice lens the heterogenous actually existing forms of everyday food activism and advocacy in the UK. We do this by uncovering and bringing into conversation diverse voices of people working to address various inequal- ities throughout the food system and unpack the ideas of jus- tice which underpin their work. This is significant, as the uti- lisation of a particular theory of justice to frame food system inequalities can open up or foreclose other ideas, visions and practices for emancipatory change (see Allen 2010; Harrison 2014; Dieterle 2015; Broad 2016). Informed by US food justice literature (Alkon and Agyeman 2011; Cadieux and Slocum 2015; Alkon and Guthman 2017; Sbicca 2018), we aim to identify the fusion and friction points in nurturing a multiscalar, reflexive and politicised UK food justice move- ment that addresses structural processes of power, privilege and oppression (Young 1990; Fraser 2008). It is hoped that this intervention will ignite a lively debate about the politics of UK food justice amongst scholar-activists, organisers, eat- ers and workers in the context of manifold contemporary socioecological crises that are produced or exacerbated by the global, industrialised food system. The paper begins with a critical examination of the politi- cal theory of justice whereby consideration is given to three key dimensions—plurality, spatial–temporal and more-than- human—to elucidate the depth and breadth of the concept. We examine how these conceptualisations of justice have been utilised in the established food justice literature and argue for greater critical engagement to expand further the geographies, scales and subjects of food justice. We then proceed to present the empirical material of the paper, pay- ing particular attention to how ‘justice’ is articulated and deployed by activists and practitioners working across the food system drawing upon 30 in-depth interviews. The final section of the paper critically reflects on what is gained or lost by adopting a broader (or plurivocal) ‘justice multiple’ 45Food justice for all?: searching for the ‘justice multiple’ in UK food movements 1 3 approach to food justice praxis and outlines avenues for future research. Interrogating political theories of ‘justice’ in food justice Recent calls for greater clarity in relation to how food jus- tice is conceptualised and practiced (Sbicca 2012; Cadieux and Slocum 2015) highlights the importance of bringing food justice into conversation with diverse literature from political philosophy that critically engages with the con- tested notion of justice (Dieterle 2015; Barnhill and Doggett 2018). In this section, we unpack three broad dimensions of justice – plurality, the spatial–temporal and the more-than- human—which we argue are crucial to expand, deepen and enrich the ways justice is conceptualised and intersects with food system issues. As Dixon (2014, p. 175) states, learning to enact food justice first necessitates that the lens of justice is attuned and refined in order to “see”, unpack and address multiple forms of inequality. We therefore conclude this section by advancing the notion of the ‘justice multiple’ to incorporate a diversity of justice framings, which are shaped by various spatial, temporal and scalar relations, to provide a basis to examine the heterogenous justice claims of UK food movement practitioners and activists. Pluralising justice: distribution, recognition, participation and enhancing capabilities In order to carefully consider the fundamental justice prin- ciples that inform the conceptual foundation of food justice, we begin by discussing the central dimension of distributive justice. Broadly speaking, the majority of Western liberal political philosophical writing on justice has been preoc- cupied with the notion of distributive justice in relation to the allocation of benefits and burdens between different indi- viduals and groups, with focus placed on (abstract) fairness and impartiality. In this context, social justice is defined as the “standard whereby the distributive aspects of the basic structure of society are to be assessed” (Rawls 1971, p. 9). The importance placed on distributive elements of food jus- tice is demonstrated by the definition put forward by Got- tlieb and Joshi (2010, p. 6) in their seminal scholarly text, as “ensuring that the benefits and risks of where, what, and how food is grown and produced, transported and distributed, and accessed and eaten are shared fairly”. Given the complex- ity and intersectional nature of oppression that permeates food systems entangled with neoliberal capitalism, systemic racism and heteropatriarchy, scholar-activists contend that addressing distributional injustices in isolation (frequently framed in terms of ‘access’) is insufficient to tackle com- plex food inequalities. Therefore, relational difference and politicised actions that are transformative of oppressive structures must be positioned at the heart of food justice (Cadieux and Slocum 2015; Sbicca 2018; Slocum 2018). This underscores a more pluralistic, embodied and less uni- versalistic notion of justice. Political theorists who have critically examined the plu- rality of justice, such as Young (1990), Fraser (1997, 2008), Schlosberg (2007) and Sen (2009), have drawn heavily upon the praxis of social movements to develop their respective theories of justice by observing the complex relations of oppression and processes of inequality that contextualise our lifeworld, rather than relying on depersonalised idealised abstraction. This vividly highlights the symbiotic relation- ship between multidimensional justice theory and diversi- fied social movement practice. Drawing upon the embodied justice claims of marginalised groups, Fraser (2005, 2008) understands justice as parity of participation, incorporat- ing three dimensions: redistribution (socioeconomic), rec- ognition (cultural-legal) and representation (political). This framework corresponds to the questions of what counts as a matter of justice, who counts as a subject of justice, and how justice claims are defined and determined. Similarly, Young (1990) advocates for a theory of justice grounded in the everyday practices of emancipatory social movements that endeavour to tackle systems of oppression. For Young (1990, p. 37), oppression is defined as “the institutional con- straint on self-development” and is characterised by “five faces”: exploitation, marginalisation, powerlessness, cultural imperialism and violence—all of which need to be addressed in relation to the food system to create more just and socio- ecologically sustainable relations (Slocum 2018). The work of Fraser (1997; Fraser and Honneth 2003) is particularly important for explicating the politics of recog- nition—a traditionally under-theorised dimension of justice in political theory. Fraser (1997) contends that recognition is both an important dimension of justice and a prerequisite for fair distribution, in which misrecognition (or lack of respect) is structural, social and symbolic—that is, a cultural and institutional form of injustice, or a “status injury”. In the context of food systems, recognitional injustices are ren- dered visible in the ways in which indigenous communities and marginalised groups have been historically subjected to cultural and political domination, discrimination and disre- spect that disrupts or devalues traditional foodways (Mares and Peña 2011). Addressing such issues requires commu- nities to exercise their right to determine their own food systems through collective leadership and participation in decision-making processes (Penniman 2018), challenging the norms and practices that (re)produce and legitimise ine- quality (Fraser and Honneth 2003) and nurturing political consciousness—or conscientisation (Freire 1970) – through critical food systems education that respects diverse knowl- edge systems. 46 H. Coulson, P. Milbourne 1 3 Procedural or participatory justice (Loo 2014) is therefore crucial, as mere inclusion in decision-making processes is not enough—emancipatory strategies are needed to empower citizens, and in particular, the most marginalised commu- nities. As Young (1990) has posited, in order for a policy to be just everyone in principle should be able to express their needs and have an effective voice in its deliberation. However, the traditional processes of formulating food and agricultural policy, particularly in the UK, and the Euro- pean Union more broadly through the Common Agricultural Policy, have been highly asymmetrical, reflecting the vested interests of agribusiness (Lang et al. 2009). Procedural jus- tice, therefore, emphasises the importance of participatory policy-making and democratic governance that enables the most marginalised to challenge elite control over policy development and pluralise the voices that shape (food) gov- ernance processes.2 Collectively, these diverse justice insights (Young 1990; Fraser 1997, 2008; Loo 2014) provide the foundation for a pluralised conceptualisation of food justice, which is not based on the top-down application of abstract norms, but enacted in situated contexts in response to multidimensional, embodied injustices. Elucidating this point further, pragmat- ically focusing on addressing what Sen (2009, p. ix) terms remediable injustices in our everyday lives, does not rely on constructing a theory of “perfect justice” to evaluate unjust institutional and social relations. Rather, realising justice entails identifying and addressing inequalities “around us which we want to eliminate” (Sen 2009, p. vii). Indeed, any ideals of justice (however framed) need to be practiced (or performed) often in messy, ongoing, quotidian ways that seek to heal and repair in our imperfect world. Developing the “capabilities approach” to justice, Sen (1999) argued Rawls (1971) ultimately failed to acknowl- edge that people are unable, for multiple reasons, to trans- late available primary goods into actual welfare-enhancing opportunities. Justice, therefore, requires bolstering basic entitlements and capabilities (in terms of resources, free- doms, opportunities and institutions) that people require to be full members of society. While the state clearly plays a key role ensuring that citizens have the capabilities to live meaningful lives, it is posited that the capabilities approach can strengthen rights-based frameworks of justice by moving focus away from ‘rights’ understood as simply abstract, for- mal, legal entitlements towards the ways in which grassroots collectives exercise those rights in everyday, situated prac- tices. This reflects a “human rights enterprise” from below (Armaline et al. 2015, p. 14) through interconnected trans- local micro-resistances. In this respect, forging cooperative relations of solidarity with those in other localities is crucial in order to create multiscalar geographies of food justice to nurture trajectories for socioecologically just futures. In the next section, we explicate the multiscalar spatial and tem- poral dimensions of justice in greater depth. Expanding justice across space and time: global duties, obligations to distant others and intergenerational rights The Westphalian conceptualisation of justice embodied in the work of Rawls has been critiqued for problematically focusing exclusively on the nation-state to the detriment of a multiscalar justice perspective (Caney 2005; Fraser 2005, 2008). Several theorists have argued for extending the Rawl- sian conception of justice as fairness beyond state borders (Pogge 1989) to account for the contemporary realities of intensified globalisation and pervasive worldwide poverty to determine our duties and obligations of justice in relation to principles of global distributive justice (Pogge 2002). This tends to appeal to the basic liberal idea that all humans hold the same moral worth and value. Accordingly, our justice obligations transcend socially constructed territorial bounda- ries (Caney 2005), in which our embeddedness within glob- ally interconnected social structures creates an interdepend- ence of shared political responsibility to address injustices (Young 2011). As Fraser (2008) argues, however, focusing merely on distributive (global) justice fails to comprehend the diverse dimensions and competing geographical scales of justice that entangle ‘global’ and ‘local’ ordinary-political injus- tices. Thus, any multiscalar understanding of justice must take into account the relational ways (in)justice is produced and performed across various spatial “power geometries” (Massey 1994). Food justice is consequently always a matter of sociospatial justice which requires “new ways of thinking about and acting to change the unjust geographies in which we live” (Soja 2010, p. 5). Food justice praxis therefore implicitly recognises the inherent multiscalar sociospatial organisation of food systems and the complex translocal power relations that shape (fluid) foodscapes in which injus- tice is always experienced in situated contexts by particular communities (Slocum et al. 2016). To be sure, the “scales of spatial justice are not separate and distinct; they interact and interweave in complex patterns” (Soja 2010, p. 46). Con- necting different ‘local’ issues of food (in)justice can con- tribute to the advancement of collective justice by scaling up and across efforts at the institutional level of (food) policy and strengthen coalition networks at multiple scales (Sbicca 2018). This requires (re)focusing attention to shared experi- ences of structural inequality, moving beyond what Harvey 2 A People’s Food Policy is an interesting example of an integrated and people-centred approach to grassroots participatory food policy- making within the UK context (see https ://www.peopl esfoo dpoli cy.org/). https://www.peoplesfoodpolicy.org/ https://www.peoplesfoodpolicy.org/ 47Food justice for all?: searching for the ‘justice multiple’ in UK food movements 1 3 (1996, p. 40) termed “militant particularisms”, and con- structing pluralistic and heterogeneous coalitions between diverse organisations and social movements across space. However, compared to the multiscalar food sovereignty movement (under the auspices of La Vía Campesina), food justice activism has tended to place less explicit emphasis on translocal solidarity processes for global justice (Slocum 2018). Against this backdrop, it is asserted that linking multi- scalar environmental sustainability concerns with other justice issues such as labour precarity and workers’ rights is central in order to create an effective transnational food justice movement (Myers and Sbicca 2015; Slocum et al. 2016; Sbicca 2018). The necessity to cultivate this form of integrated solidarity-building exists within a broader neo- liberal political-economic context of the intensified pursuit of global labour ‘flexibility’, income insecurity, workfare policies and the fragmentation of social entitlements (Ciplet and Harrison 2020). Thus, the push for greater focus on the multiscalar sociospatial relations of translocal solidar- ity (Slocum et al. 2016) is crucial given that food justice scholarship draws heavily on discrete ‘local’ food projects predominately in urban contexts of the US to develop its insights (Glennie and Alkon 2018), rather than the intercon- nected relationality of place (Massey 1994) and the multi- scalar power-geometries of food systems. The latter of which deserves far greater critical scrutiny. Crucially, our justice obligations also extend across time looking both to past injustices to challenge historical trauma and forward with regard to future generations (Cadieux and Slocum 2015; Penniman 2018). Debates regarding inter- generational justice have unfolded in political philosophy in relation to the possibility of extending rights to future peo- ple in the context of the “non-identity problem” (see Parfit [1984] 2004). Political theorists have, therefore, increasingly advocated for a more critical and fundamental focus on the creation of intergenerationally just policies (Schuppert 2011) that safeguard peoples fundamental interests, liberties and needs across temporalities.3 The extension of egalitarian jus- tice to future generations can be seen as a logical result of cosmopolitan intragenerational justice theorists who argue that people’s location in space should not restrict our justice obligations (Caney 2005); accordingly, people’s position in time is equally arbitrary (Caney 2009). These insights con- textualise the complex intra-/inter-generational justice issues that emerge at the socioecological intersection of a climate emergency and unsustainable food systems. As the concept of sustainability is inherently normative, what should be sustained for future generations reflects dif- ferent situated values, and consequently, is highly contested. The notion of “just sustainabilities” (Agyeman et al. 2003) emerged in relation to the environmental justice movement and has been instrumental in explicitly politicising sus- tainability by emphasising the necessity of simultaneously working towards social justice and environmental sustain- ability. While the movement has transcended narrow lib- eral Rawlsian interpretations of distributive justice (Walker 2009), justice continues to be predominately conceptualised in primarily anthropocentric terms. In this respect, the work of Pellow (2014) is important in extending the environmen- tal justice framework to incorporate nonhuman actors and directing focus towards socioecological inequality across species and space. In the following section, we outline recent developments in political theory that have incorporated the more-than-human in relation to justice and highlight current food justice scholarship that is engaging with, and develop- ing, these debates in interesting ways. Extending justice to the more‑than‑human: posthuman social justice and nonhuman vitality The conceptual separation of ‘nature’ from ‘society’ has shaped anthropocentric framings of justice that posit the social in humanistic terms that disregards nonhuman (political) agency (Latour 2005). Thus, several scholars have worked to incorporate nonhuman concerns into justice frameworks. For example, Schlosberg (2007) has argued for expanding the capabilities approach (Sen 1999; Nussbaum 2000, 2006) to the more-than-human by recognising the interconnected injustices experienced in complex relational ecologies that impede the basic capabilities and functioning of animal and plant life. Moreover, ecological justice (Baxter 2005) highlights the complex ethical and moral questions that emerge when considering nonhumans as subjects of justice. This links with the systems thinking and integrated ethical framework of earth care, people care and fair share embodied in permaculture (Holmgren 2011), which provides a socioecological lens to articulate the ecological dimen- sions of our understanding of social justice (Millner 2017). Indeed, recent developments in food justice scholarship have increasingly highlighted that justice-orientated claims, such as the right to food, requires operating from the position of the inextricably socionatural world we inhabit relationally with a multiplicity of others, whereby food is “constituted through material histories of human and nonhuman collabo- ration” (Millner 2017, p. 780). Unlike moral philosophy (see Singer’s 1975 classic text), Western political philosophy has largely failed to reflect crit- ically in relation to humanity’s pervasive sense of “species entitlement” (Kymlicka and Donaldson 2016, p. 692), and 3 The Well-being of Future Generations (Wales) Act (2015) is notable for enshrining in legislation the obligation of public bodies in Wales to place sustainable development and the consideration of the long- term impacts of decision-making on current and future generations, at its core. 48 H. Coulson, P. Milbourne 1 3 therefore, ascertain obstacles to improve justice for animals (however, see for example, Nussbaum 2006; Donaldson and Kymlicka 2011; Garner 2013). Political philosophy has tended to hold that nonhuman animals do not directly place justice demands on us, despite their ethical standing (Plunkett 2016). While Nussbaum (2006) endeavoured to extend the capabilities approach embodied in her cosmo- politan theory of justice to nonhuman animals and intermit- tently discusses the possibility for “interspecies sociability”, ultimately an anthropocentric understanding of the demos is maintained (Pepper 2016). Disrupting pervasive anthro- pocentric imaginaries of ‘the political’, as Kymlicka and Donaldson (2016) argue, involves asking difficult questions in relation to the potential political status of non-linguistic agents (such as sentient nonhuman animals) in terms of voice, participation and agency. Food justice scholarship, however, has generally remained conspicuously silent on how interspecies sociability can inform broader conceptions of justice in relation to food systems (however, see Millner 2017; Perz et al. 2018; Rodríguez 2018; Broad 2019). Bringing food justice into conversation with critical ani- mal studies provides one productive terrain to focus attention to the intersectionality of all forms of oppression includ- ing sexism, speciesism and racism (Pellow 2014; Perz et al. 2018). Unpacking the more-than-human forms of injustice embedded in the “animal-industrial complex” (Twine 2012, p. 15) that exploits animals for purposes of corporate capi- tal accumulation and the differential ecological and social inequalities that emerge from such a system, provides one avenue to expand understandings of food justice to nonhu- mans. In short, it is contended that in order to hold food justice activism accountable on the ‘justice’ dimension, working towards equitable and sustainable food systems must secure justice for humans and nonhumans (Rodríguez 2018). Recent work by Broad (2019, p. 225) in relation to the intersection of animal product alternatives and food jus- tice – what he terms “food tech justice” – provides an inter- esting (albeit contested) example of one agenda that seeks to explore the possibilities for “food system health, equity, and sustainability” beyond animal agriculture. Food systems, therefore, provide a pertinent, embodied and vital lens to examine how we can/do/do not live respon- sibly in multispecies worlds at various ‘contact zones’—the places where species meet (Haraway 2008)—such as agri- food systems. Drawing upon insights from new material- ism (Bennett 2010; Coole and Frost 2010), scholars have argued that taking the agency or vitality of nonhumans seriously (Plumwood 2001)—for example, by exposing the more-than-human agencies of soil in the politics of food systems—is crucial in order to foster more just and sustain- able socioecological relations (Ferguson and the Northern Rivers Landed Histories Research Group 2016). This creates new political terrains for social transformation beyond the nature/society dichotomy in ways that expand the parameters of justice to nonhuman life. To summarise, encouraged by Schlosberg’s (2007, p. 165) insight that “a plurality of discourses of justices is a good thing” and informed by scholar-activists who argue for a multifaceted justice lens (Sbicca 2018), in this paper we posit that plural, spatial–temporal (or intra-/inter-gener- ational) and more-than-human conceptions of justice should be more robustly examined and fully integrated into food justice praxis. This can inform broader diverse “counter narratives” (Dixon 2014, p. 175) that expand the who and what of food justice claims and activism, and nuance how they are defined and determined (Fraser 2008), and there- fore, what interventions are enacted to address “remediable injustices” (Sen 2009, p. vii). Accordingly, an understanding of the justice multiple (cf. Mol 2002) that focuses on the diverse everyday practices, experiences and understandings that are constitutive of human and nonhuman justice is use- ful for examining the manifold and competing rationales that shape who participates in deciding what a just food system looks like and how it can be engendered, across both space and time. Indeed, what is ‘fair’ or ‘just’ in relation to food sys- tems is not complete, consistent or culturally universal, but instead always partial, situated and contextually embedded, reflecting diverse values, normative ideals and priorities (Harrison 2014). Thus, in this paper we examine how food justice is interpreted, mobilised and enacted by different actors involved with heterogenous UK food movements by applying the justice multiple lens. This is crucial, we argue, given that compared to North American food studies litera- ture (see, for example, Guthman 2008; Allen 2010; Holt- Giménez 2011; Holt-Giménez and Shattuck 2011; Broad 2016; Sbicca 2018), there is a notable paucity of critical food justice scholarship unpacking the contested terrain of UK food movements and their justice claims, which this paper seeks to address. Researching conceptualisations of justice in UK food movements The empirical section of this paper draws upon the find- ings from 30 in-depth semi-structured interviews with food movement practitioners and activists working at the local, regional and national levels across the UK. Relatively few groups explicitly frame their work as ‘food justice’ in the UK, and therefore, participants were identified through a web-based search of diverse food-related advocacy groups, non-governmental organisations (NGOs), and coalition net- works that are working to address various (social, economic, and environmental) injustices in the food system. A database of potential organisations was compiled based on a search of 49Food justice for all?: searching for the ‘justice multiple’ in UK food movements 1 3 key topics, including food access, food poverty, food policy, land use, labour/work, and alternative food practices. This search captured a range of activities, projects and initiatives, concerning food security, environmental sustainability, ani- mal welfare, and labour struggles within the food chain. Fur- thermore, multiple alternative food practices were identified that focus on different aspects and (contested) qualities of food such as local, organic, slow, non-genetically modified organisms (GMO) and cruelty-free. The main aim of the interviews was to discern what activists and food movement practitioners4 mean when they employ the concept ‘justice’ in relation to their work, and therefore, examine how different theories of justice are utilised to shape social action. Thus, interviews cen- tred upon the meaning, relevance and content of the term ‘justice’ in relation to participants’ advocacy and everyday practices. The interviews were undertaken from February to August 2018 and each lasted between 60 and 95  min and were audio-recorded and transcribed verbatim. Of the 30 people interviewed, 12 were women and 18 men with the majority White-British, highlighting the intersectional privilege that permeates mainstream food movements. The transcripts were analysed through two rounds of thematic coding, the first to identify key themes and ascertain ideas of justice explicitly or implicitly articulated in the narratives, and the second, to refine codes related to aspects of justice identified in the literature review: redistribution, recogni- tion, participation, capabilities, spatial (intra-generational), temporal (inter-generational), and more-than-human. The following results section is structured around the different justice themes that emerged from the analysis based on the expanded conceptualisation of the justice multiple. Quota- tions from the interviews5 are utilised to highlight the central issues and topics uncovered from the research. Examining justice in UK food movements Pluralising justice through rights‑based approaches to food The global food and financial crisis of 2007–8 was identified by the majority of participants as the catalyst for increased practitioner and activist interest in contemporary food sys- tem inequalities. For some anti-hunger organisations, the very presence and prevalence of emergency food aid projects and charitable welfare provision signifies a fracturing wel- fare system that no longer provides security for those who need it (Poppendieck 1998). This was articulated in relation to a broader critique of the current ‘austere’ political-eco- nomic context, which is fundamentally “unfair and broken” (practitioner, national food NGO; see also O’Hara 2014; Raj 2019). Yet, for those involved with charitable food projects on the ground, their everyday focus was aligned to increas- ing access to food to meet an immediate need drawing pri- marily on notions of distributive (in)justice that emphasise the unfair allocation of material foodstuffs. As a manager of a franchised food bank located in the north east of England explained, their priority was addressing acute experiences of food insecurity: “we are a first responder in many ways for that food crisis”. For some interviewees, it was much easier to identify an apparent lived form of remediable injustice (Sen 2009) such as a lack of access to food and respond to it through everyday acts of kindness, collective action or voluntarism, which they believed did not necessarily reflect expressions of ‘justice’. Several practitioners explained that, in their experience, communities were often averse to frame or communicate inequalities explicitly in terms of (in)justice, as a policy director for a human rights and social justice charity stated, “because it is perceived as very confrontational and elit- ist, perhaps legalistic”. It was proposed that the notion of fairness is much more intuitive, compared to framing food inequalities as a violation of human rights. Some practition- ers, therefore, argued that people should be empowered as “rights holders” (campaigns manager, social justice charity) to demand access to food and a range of other entitlements as central to living a nourished and dignified life. However, as a community activist involved with a grassroots food project stated, there is a need for a “change in culture” in how we communicate food inequalities, whereby people feel comfortable to connect and articulate food issues to vital matters of social (in)justice (Raj 2019). For those who focused on justice, rather than the food dimension of food injustice, a lack of economic rather than physical access was conveyed as the crucial factor that impeded food security. Notably, precarious employment opportunities, in-work poverty and punitive austerity poli- cies that underpin economic injustice were described as an inhibiting factor encumbering peoples participation in an ‘alternative’ food movement that continues to fetishize the commodification of food for profit (Agyeman and McEn- tee 2014). As a chief executive for a national food NGO discussed, in practice “there is a gap between the local and sustainable or seasonable produce [sector] and access for low income communities […] the sustainable food move- ment in Britain is just so small and niche that it struggles to provide that food at an affordable price point that’s acces- sible to most people”. This creates a schism between the 4 We use the term ‘practitioner’ to denote a paid employee of a NGO or alternative food initiative and ‘activist’ when utilised by the indi- vidual as a self-ascribed identifier. 5 As participants continue to play an active role in UK food move- ment politics they are anonymised to ensure confidentiality. 50 H. Coulson, P. Milbourne 1 3 priorities of projects focusing on the immediate provision of food and the ‘alternative’ consumptive politics that domi- nates environmental sustainability movements that typically discussed their social action as “reconnecting production and consumption in sustainable ways” (farmer, community- supported agriculture scheme). In terms of the latter, food movement practitioners involved with organisations and projects focusing on the creation of localised food systems tended to emphasise mainstream environmentalism priorities and overlooked or downplayed social justice considerations. For organisations and networks that adopted an explicit food justice frame (who remain a small and fragmented minority in the UK), connecting distributive, participative and recognitional (in)justice was crucial in order to move beyond a narrow focus on food access to incorporate “indi- vidual and community empowerment, dignity and political representation to [develop] the more collective right to a fair food system” (campaigns manager, food justice organi- sation). This is imperative in a highly unequal society in which differences in power and recognition exclude the most marginalised from decision-making processes, as a director of a permaculture NGO stated: “where’s the political voice of those one and a half million people using food banks?”. As described by an activist involved with a grassroots food policy movement, creating a holistic framework to convene multiple interests as they relate to food is vital for exploring fusion and friction points for developing solidarity towards food justice: “How do you find the thread that links people who are using a food bank with a farmer who might also be in destitution and on the brink of having to sell up? There’s actually a certain sort of commonality between them”. In this context, identifying the structural causes of inequal- ity (re)produced by the political economy of food, enables diverse groups to acknowledge shared injustice; particularly the corporate food regime that entangles neo-productivist logics of agricultural intensification, the commodification of the commons (such as seeds) and promotes institutionalised food aid, which constructs food poverty as a matter of indi- vidualised scarcity, rather than systemic inequity. The notion of ‘empowerment’ in terms of how it is expressed, enacted and experienced in food-related grass- roots initiatives provides a particularly contested terrain for addressing participative, recognitional and representa- tional injustice. For example, when critically reflecting on their involvement in advocacy tackling food poverty, an empowerment programme officer for an anti-poverty pro- ject commented: Are you truly empowering people? Or is it just a con- sultation that actually decisions have already been made? […] Overall, it is giving a stronger voice to those with experiences in food poverty, and under- standing that they’re the real experts, in terms of the actual injustices on the ground […] people growing up in poverty are those who are continuously disem- powered. This participant emphasised the intersecting axes of dif- ference (such as class, gender and (dis)ability) that contex- tualise the accumulated quotidian, embodied processes of disempowerment that some people experience over their life-course, which can have significant long-term detrimental impacts on their mental and physical health, and reinforce participatory injustice. Some NGOs have, therefore, devised strategies to nurture grassroots discussions of rights-based approaches to food justice, for example, organising partici- pative workshops with those most absent from food sys- tem discussions, as a coordinator of a civil society coalition working for food justice described: we’ve been working with people who are tradition- ally excluded from the decision-making processes and who are likely to face much more complex food jus- tice issues. […] we’ve been listening to peoples’ food injustice experiences, and their solutions to deal with those issues […] to embed this experience into policy and law. In particular, Kitchen Table Talks, which are informal and convivial forums for citizens to discuss food (in)justice in diverse accessible spaces (such as allotments, community food hubs and cafes) were identified as important platforms to nurture inclusive, democratic, people-centred food policy- making. The process of fostering procedural or participative (food) justice in practice can be challenging, however, as articulated by a policy manager for a food justice organisa- tion, because “the term ‘food justice’ is still in its infancy in Scotland, and we’re continually trying to work out how we communicate these complex ideas in an accessible way that is genuinely meaningful for people”. Moreover, some practitioners acknowledged that in a sociospatial context whereby many people feel disenfranchised from mainstream politics, bringing together heterogenous voices to develop inclusive and diverse food movement politics – by reaching beyond the middle-class privilege that has tended to domi- nate food activist spaces and networks – can be a challenging and slow (but imperative) process to realising participatory food justice. In relation to their everyday work practices, several par- ticipants emphasised the importance of placing dignity and respect as core principles underpinning their advocacy and basing their organisational agenda on the lived experiences of people beyond the ‘mainstream’ food movement. This is exemplified by the Menu for Change6 project’s emphasis on 6 A Menu for Change was a partnership project (2017–19) estab- lished as a response to the proliferation of emergency food aid and increasing levels of hunger in Scotland (delivered by Oxfam Scotland, 51Food justice for all?: searching for the ‘justice multiple’ in UK food movements 1 3 “Cash, Rights, Food” to address the root causes of food inse- curity (see MacLeod 2019, p. 7), in which women, and lone parents in particular, are disproportionately affected (Inde- pendent Working Group on Food Poverty 2016). As a cam- paigns manager from a food justice organisation described, “empowering communities is essential to ensure people meaningfully participate in political processes that affect their everyday lives […] based on [values of] co-production and dignity, where a holistic rights-based framework is fun- damental to move towards food justice”. Notably, the majority of participants articulated their understanding of ‘food justice’ in terms of the universal (and fundamentally anthropocentric) right to food, as stated by a practitioner working for an international anti-poverty organi- sation: “I think everybody should have enough to eat is a basic human right, access to food, I guess it’s a rights-based approach […] there is enough food to go around, it’s just the distribution of it is skewed”. This interviewee, along with many others, elaborated the importance of understanding distributive inequities in a global context that transcended arbitrary socially constructed boundaries as a matter of fair- ness (Caney 2005). This sentiment was reiterated by a direc- tor of a permaculture organisation who commented: “the issue globally is not food supply, we grow enough calories to feed everybody, the issue is food distribution” and as a small-scale farmer explained, “you have to start from the point of view that the right to sufficient, adequate and high- quality food is a basic human right”. Overall, interviewees framed the right to food in terms of fairness and equality drawing on liberal understandings of justice (as found in the work of Rawls). In Scotland, there is growing momentum to enshrine the right to food within Scottish legislation through the Good Food Nation agenda.7 As a campaigns manager for a food justice organisation comments, this campaigning priority was justified because: “if you don’t design a food system which is to progress people’s rights, then we will only ever be tinkering around the edges […] we’d like a framework that enables a constant progress towards the progressive realisation of the right to food”. Legislation, therefore, was viewed as a vital vehicle for establishing a core (govern- mental), long-term commitment towards a fair, healthy and sustainable food system, necessitating a coherent and transparent governance framework to ensure accountabil- ity based on “national and local strategies and the right to food as a minimum core obligation” (policy director, social justice charity). While the discourse of ‘rights’ challenges narratives of charitable food (aid) – and enshrining the right to food in law makes policy more resilient and robust as governments change over the political lifecycle – without undoing the structures of power that reproduce inequality, institutionalising the right to food will not guarantee that people are nourished in practice. In this context, some interviewees discussed how a per- formative collective grassroots food politics of “community- led initiatives such as community gardens or like a really good community café or food cooperative that runs along- side the credit union” (organisational lead, community food NGO) often work to guarantee ‘rights’ such as access to nutritious, socially acceptable, culturally appropriate and affordable food in specific, contextual circumstances, rather than relying on the state to do so. This embodies a prefigura- tive “human rights enterprise” from below (Armaline et al. 2015) based on tackling hunger, food insecurity and social isolation as remediable injustices (Sen 2009), which can be addressed in the here and now through collective action, thus creating a situated sense of food justice that endeavours to nurture people’s existing capabilities (Sen 1999; Nussbaum 2000). As noted by several community activists, these grass- roots practices occur in a broader context whereby the UK Government violates a range of legally required obligations to “respect, protect and fulfil” the right to food imposed by international human rights frameworks8 (Just Fair 2014). Enacting sociospatial (food) justice: labour rights, consumptive politics and the invisibility of workers Embedding struggles for economic justice in the local food movement creates particular tension points between labour unions advocating for greater economic equity and those aligning with consumption-based food politics. As described by a labour activist, supporters of alternative food initiatives frequently overlook or disregard conventional food-chain workers because their labour is associated with corporate power and bolsters a socio-environmentally undesirable food system. This tension is exemplified by the McStrike campaign,9 whereby a privileged, biopolitical consump- tive imaginary pervades the mainstream food movement 7 This relates to the campaigning agenda of NGOs within Scotland for a Good Food Nation Bill based on a coordinated approach to food policy. 8 For example, the 1966 International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights outlines the right to food in Article 11 and was ratified by the UK Government in 1976. 9 A coalition of trade unions and civil society organisations enacting collective action in relation to low pay, precarious work, bullying and harassment in the workplace, and also a fight for union recognition across the fast food sector, accumulating in days of strike action in the UK since 2015 (for example, on 4 September 2017 and 4 October 2018). The Poverty Alliance, Nourish Scotland and Child Poverty Action Group in Scotland). Footnote 6 (continued) 52 H. Coulson, P. Milbourne 1 3 and artificially separates the ‘alternative’ from the ‘conven- tional’ food system, impeding broader support and acts of solidarity. As an economic justice campaign officer for an anti-poverty charity comments: there is quite a big education job to get people to understand that the role of these campaigns isn’t just to direct individuals’ consumption choices, so in one way that is the failure of our food movement to success- fully articulate a position that marries workers’ rights within fast food with that broader desire to transform the food system, because far too often that falls within an organic consumption, consumer-led type activity […] some of the frames within that are problematic for generating and mobilising support for it. The relative ‘invisibility’ and the devaluing of fast food work compared to, for example, the consideration and arti- san skill associated with the Slow Food movement and its focus on “good, clean, fair food” (member, Slow Food Cymru) “as the ‘gold standard’ of food preparation labour at both home and in restaurants” (Thiemann and Roman-Alcalá 2019, p. 814) works to reinforce food privilege and devalue particular forms of labour that occupies differential positions throughout the food system. Thus, as a practitioner from a food justice organisation argued, it is crucial to identify syn- ergies between the exploitation of labour “on farms, super- markets, slaughterhouses and restaurants, […] throughout complex supply chains” in order to position labour justice more centrally within food movement praxis. However, as a food activist described, “connecting rural and urban is a really big piece of the jigsaw that is often missing” in nurtur- ing translocal, cross-sectoral worker solidarity. A key aspect of economic injustice that was expressed by many participants was the prevalence of in-work poverty. As a public affairs officer for an international Christian charity stated, those working in the food sector often “can’t afford to feed themselves because they are too stretched financially”. In-work poverty currently affects four million people in the UK, the highest in 20 years (JRF 2018). Pertinently, the pov- erty rate is the highest for people employed in food-related industries, with 25 percent of those working in accommo- dation and food services and 23 percent in agriculture, for- estry and fishing, categorised as living in poverty (JRF 2018, p. 36). As a director of a permaculture NGO elucidated: “There’s a huge irony that the people who are paid the least are the people who work in the food industry and that works from farmers through to the people, the cashiers, who sit on the tills, so there’s something deeply broken”. While manifestations of economic inequality that permeate the food system were broadly recognised by participants, their involvement with collective, concerted and integrated action to address labour injustices was fragmented and limited. For some, critical food system education was imperative to enable people to (re)value agrifood labour based on nur- turing political conscientisation (Freire 1970), particularly in the context of a highly industrialised society such as the UK. As described by a food activist in relation to agricultural labour, “we assign so much value and prestige to office jobs, rather than working with our hands, food production, gar- dening is badly paid, so low-status jobs […] it’s all about our values”. Mainstream ‘local’ food movement practitioners, however, rarely discussed equitable conditions of food-chain workers or agricultural labour, rendering multiple forms of food system labour ‘hidden’, reflecting their structural and spatial invisibility in ‘placeless’ factories or remote fields. As a labour activist involved with an anti-poverty charity asserts, food justice can only be attained by revaluing food work in all its forms, paying particular attention to those low-paid, low-skilled sectors outside the purview of ‘local food’ imaginaries: “hospitality is one of those areas with very low wages and very high uses of the most insecure types of work, often marginalised workers, whether that’s because of gender and migrant status as well”. In the UK, the annual need for seasonal agricultural work- ers is a permanent occurrence, however, they are rendered provisional and transitory – the migrant precariat. As a small-scale farmer commented, “There’s been this essen- tially quite racist stuff about Eastern Europeans [in populist Brexit narratives] and then everyone trying to figure out ways of […] allowing Eastern European labour migration to continue despite […] not wanting it to”. While increasing emphasis has been placed on the centrality of migrant labour to UK agriculture, processing and catering, they remain largely invisible and voiceless in debates over the future of post-Brexit food policy, highlighting the participative and recognitional injustices that marginalised groups experience (Loo 2014). Indeed, given that farming10 in the UK is the least ethnically diverse occupation, whereby 98.6 percent are classified as White-British compared to 80.1 percent of total population share (Norrie 2017), there is a pressing need to expand solidarity of agricultural work beyond the white privilege of farm ownership (and large, corporate-focused farming unions) to the marginalised migrant workers that the agricultural system relies upon. Hence, protecting the rights of migrant workers throughout the food chain is particularly important in the context of zero-hour contracts, piecework and Brexit: “We’re really keen that migrant workers aren’t receiving different minimum wages and receiving different conditions” (policy manager, food justice organisation) and through advocacy “draw attention to the overlap between precarious work and other forms of marginalisation, whether 10 Significantly, this category does not include farmworkers or fruit- pickers, many of whom are from Eastern Europe. 53Food justice for all?: searching for the ‘justice multiple’ in UK food movements 1 3 that is race, gender or migration status, and how precari- ous work, works as a system to reinforce those oppressions” (economic justice campaign officer, anti-poverty charity). Through transnational alliances for labour justice, we begin to see how responsibility for global labour justice (Fraser 2005, 2008) can be enacted. As a general secretary for a trade union involved in the McStrike describes: “the SEIU [Service Employees International Union] have been an absolute pivotal part of our campaign, because they support us, send us over trainers to show us how to organise in the fast food arena, they have brought their activists over here to stand on picket-lines and demonstrations outside differ- ent McDonalds stores, they have really been an inspiration to us”. McStrike action took place across towns and cities seeking to strengthen a fair wages movement for food work- ers in the UK, but also enacted in solidarity with the US living wage campaign (the ‘Fight for $15′), with a productive exchange of knowledge and capacity-building processes that were discussed as central to fostering international labour solidarity in relation to sociospatial justice (Slocum et al. 2016). Notably, a small number of participants discussed the importance of moving beyond the labour-based “mili- tant particularisms” (Harvey 1996) that can be embodied in traditional worker organisations such as trade unions, which can impede broader coalition-building with groups campaigning for the transition to a sustainable, decarbon- ised economy (Ciplet and Harrison 2020). This ‘sectoral’ fragmentation can ultimately encumber struggles for radical food system transformation. Connecting concerns for the local with the global is cen- tral to examining the injustices embedded throughout inter- national food supply chains that transverse ‘alternative’ and ‘conventional’ food systems. As an advocacy officer for an anti-poverty organisation comments, the interconnected, multiscalar nature of food systems means that any interven- tion in one place must consider the (global) justice dimen- sions of actions within, and across, nation-state boundaries: [a key task is] how to connect the stuff we are doing locally with the global picture […] which is looking at the treatment of people within food supply chains […]. We’ve done some research in Wales, for example, on women’s low paid sector work, of which food is one, and how to link those two things together to show that there is a price for cheap food here and there is a price globally as well […]. Even if supermarkets are paying the living wage and have decent work in the UK, it doesn’t necessarily mean that that follows all the way through their supply chains. The limited capacity of NGOs and activists in terms of time, resources and knowledge of campaigns in other socio- spatial contexts were obstacles identified by practitioners that can encumber cultivating connections of trust, solidarity and relations of translocal food justice in practice within and between countries. This demonstrates the complexity of enacting responsibility towards harms and injustices involv- ing distant strangers (Young 2011) from the position of a progressive global sense of place (Massey 1994). Transforming food systems through socioecological justice: extending justice to the more‑than‑human For those who articulated a more-than-human conception of food justice, diverse mobilisations emerged around ani- mal activism (particularly animal rights and animal welfare advocates) and environmental/ecological justice. The former was discussed as a moral and ethical stance towards sen- tient nonhuman animals and the latter rooted in concerns for the destructive impacts of industrial, chemically-intensive agriculture on more-than-human ecologies. For some par- ticipants, the complicated and uneven power relations that entangle humans with other animals creates specific ethi- cal and justice obligations dedicated to animal liberation approaches under the “animal-industrial complex” (Twine 2012). This is embodied by veganism that frames justice in terms of animal rights: “the key thing for us is considering the justice and rights of animals […] trying to attain justice for the voiceless animals within our food system […]. So we want to see a complete end to any form of exploitation, of all cruelty to animals” (manager, national vegan charity). In terms of participatory injustice, this interviewee identified nonhuman animals as the paradigmatic ‘voiceless’ margin- alised group entangled in food system politics. While vegan advocacy has conventionally radiated from the core ethical arguments of animal sentiency, those involved with vegan and vegetarian organisations discussed several factors that have been instrumental in diffusing veganism beyond animal rights concerns, most notably, environmental sustainability and health considerations, which have facilitated greater interest in more plant-based consumption. In particular, vegan activists discussed the importance of connecting the injustice and oppression experienced by agricultural animals to farmworkers and ecosystems, and articulated “the benefits of moving away from animal farming and towards plant protein agriculture [and] coming up with solutions to ensure that farmers can have a sustainable lifestyle […] there’s a perception that we are anti-farming… which we’re not” (campaigner, vegan NGO). This tension was discussed in relation to ensuring that farmers have support to transition towards plant protein agriculture and safeguard sustainable livelihoods (Rodríguez 2018; Broad 2019). Significantly, given the definitive ethico- political position of veganism (for example, regarding the moral treatment of animals), it was discussed by a manager of a national vegan charity that there were ethically defended barriers to building certain alliances, as campaigns such as 54 H. Coulson, P. Milbourne 1 3 “less and better meat and dairy does clash with our values”, resulting in various vegan groups and activists believing they occupy the ‘margins’ of the dominant UK food movement. The material reality and ethical implications of killing animals exposes the complex terrain of justice claims that contextualise the idea of a ‘humane’ or ‘compassionate’ death. This narrative was most vividly expressed by ani- mal welfare groups (who focus on regulation and protection policies) concerning interspecies relations, as a practitioner for an animal welfare organisation stated: “we are opposed to long distance animal transport and inhumane slaughter […] their welfare must be taken into account, so protect- ing animals as sentient beings”. In this context, protecting nonhuman animals’ welfare was discussed as ensuring their “capacity to perform natural functions, [and] live a digni- fied life” (policy manager, animal welfare organisation). This formulates animals as subjects of political justice as reflected by the capabilities approach extended to the more- than-human (Nussbaum 2006). It is important to note that such animal-orientated justice considerations (based on the recognition of the sentience and moral worth of nonhuman animals) were mostly absent from other food movement interviewee narratives that drew upon predominately anthro- pocentric understandings of justice, highlighting a particu- lar obstacle in fostering justice for humans and nonhumans entangled within the food system (Rodríguez 2018). The role of the neoliberal political economy in shaping the agricultural industrial complex that promotes the inten- sification of farming was also highlighted as a crucial factor in exploiting and degrading one of the most foundational actants in food systems – soil. As a director of an environ- mental network charity describes: “the other justice aspect that hasn’t been considered are things like the impact of this [agricultural intensification] on soils. […] there might only be 60 harvests left in our soils globally, and so constantly over-fertilising and taking the maximum out of that […] we’re losing soil at a huge rate”. While this highlights a heightened awareness of the vitality of nonhuman material- ity such as soil and the intergenerational consequences of unsustainable farming practices, it still embodies an anthro- pocentric concern for future agricultural output. Decentring the human requires nurturing nonhuman vitality (Plumwood 2001; Bennett 2010) beyond the instrumentalist agricultural paradigm, and instead understanding ‘resources’ in a more- than-human relational context (Slocum et al. 2016). Agroecological practices based on diverse situated knowl- edges, and permaculture in particular, were described by some as a “radical challenge to the mainstream liberal, capitalist model” of food production (practitioner, perma- culture NGO). In this context, several community activists stressed that a growing number of grassroots food initiatives are adopting justice-orientated agroecological frameworks, and therefore, can play a crucial role in creating inclusive, nurturing and healing sociospatial relations that address social and ecological justice together (Holmgren 2011). This is vital given that very few groups and organisations adopt a systemic approach to food-related issues and chal- lenges. As an anti-GMO campaigner discussed, despite people approaching the food system from different entry points “which is why the subject is often fragmented into small, specialist groups”, placing advocacy and activism in a broader landscape of just sustainability (Agyeman et al. 2003) provides a holistic foundation to build solidarity and develop connections in the context of intergenerational jus- tice. As an activist involved with the anti-GMO movement explained: We don’t just talk about GMO, but put it into the context of just sustainability, because in our view it is a symptom of a system that has failed to take up the challenge of producing food in an agroecological and just way. […] [and we] put food in the context of wildlife, health, hunger and malnutrition, and the use of pesticides and climate change […] in which we all have a stake because it affects our future health. In this sense, coalitions that draw together multiple cam- paigns, advocacy work and projects that reflect the diver- sity of actually existing food activism and situate it within a broader (socioecological) justice framework were discussed by several activists as crucial in forging collective power and developing strategic interventions within the policy and gov- ernance landscape. This form of connectivity, however, is currently sparse in practice. Therefore, a fundamental chal- lenge to cultivating food justice in the UK and addressing the structural, more-than-human injustices that shape food and farming systems lies in building collective momentum, strengthening alliances and creating political spaces to con- vene multiple interests in order to overcome fragmented social movement organising. The justice multiple in UK food movements Recent scholarship has called for a wider interpretation of food justice, incorporating distribution, recognition, par- ticipation and capability-based dimensions to strengthen avenues for collective solidarity (Sbicca 2018). However, there is a paucity of engagement with the multifaceted and extensive body of critical political theory that examines the complexity, meaning and nuance of justice and how this relates to, and can inform, food justice praxis in particular socio-spatial contexts (Dieterle 2015; Barnhill and Doggett 2018). Thus, we have posited that plural, spatial–temporal (or intra-/inter-generational) and more-than-human con- ceptions of justice should be more fully integrated into a broader notion of food justice. We propose the idea of the 55Food justice for all?: searching for the ‘justice multiple’ in UK food movements 1 3 justice multiple to draw attention to the entangled web of co- dependencies in which (food) justice can only be achieved when relations of exploitation and the root causes of sys- tems of oppression are addressed through manifold, inter- connected contextual practices of justice, while acknowl- edging difference, diverse knowledges and uneven power relations (Young 1990; Fraser 2008). Indeed, the social, environmental and economic inequalities of the global food system demands that food justice is approached inclusively and holistically, connecting diverse  sociospatial situated activism and advocacy within an integrated framework of socioecological justice. While the concept of food justice is increasingly drawn upon by a range of actors to connect food to crucial mat- ters of injustice (such as poverty), there is a lack of clarity in terms of what exactly food justice is, and what it should look like, in the UK context (Kneafsey et al. 2017). Our research demonstrates that food movement practitioners predominately understand ‘food justice’ in terms of the uni- versal, abstract and anthropocentric right to food, in which all human beings should have access to sufficient, safe and nutritious food regardless of spatial location. Exploring how justice is deployed by actors in relation to their work in practice highlights that the explicit language of justice is often replaced with notions of access, fairness, empower- ment, rights and dignity linked to their programmatic focus. This differential articulation of justice frequently reflects the established organisational discursive framings and frag- mented nature of advocacy and activism, which tends to focus on particular food system issues. Rights-based approaches have gained particular momen- tum among grassroots activists and organisations in the UK, building on academic scholarship advocating for rights-based frameworks to address food poverty (Dowler and Lambie-Mumford 2015). This is exemplified by advo- cacy currently underway in Scotland, whereby community groups, charities and individuals are campaigning for a legal framework for the progressive realisation of the right to food through the Good Food Nation agenda. The notion of dignity – understood as respect and a sense of meaningful agency – was frequently reiterated by participants in relation to food systems to denote the necessity of everyone having digni- fied access to adequate, nutritious and culturally appropriate food, whereby the right to food is a matter of justice, rather than charity. More broadly, this draws attention towards the role of the state and issues of governance, regulation and accountability in relation to rights-based frameworks for addressing structural inequalities. Therefore, we suggest future research must untangle the complex (oppositional and supportive) relationships emerging between food (justice) activism and the state (across the devolved nations), paying close attention to possible processes of co-option and de- politicising mechanisms. The transformative capacity of the right to food agenda will rest not only on its ability to empower citizens and protect and respect the interdependency of different human rights, but also the co-dependencies of socioecological entanglements that form ‘the environment’ (Schlosberg 2007; Millner 2017), nurturing an inclusive rights-based enterprise from below (Armaline et  al. 2015) based on the pluralistic recognition of diverse values and rights of humans and nonhumans to live a dignified life. Our research revealed, however, that while it is imperative to expand conceptions of food justice to nonhuman nature (Rodríguez 2018), in practice, placing nonhumans as subjects of justice frequently remains confined to activists or practitioners who explicitly frame their advocacy in relation to animal rights or ecological justice. Therefore, a key challenge remains in enacting plurivocal food justice praxis which recognises and protects the diverse rights of peoples and nonhuman natures, and systematically connects concerns for sustainable diets, animal welfare, environmental health, labour justice and the decarbonisation of the economy – in other words, pursu- ing sustainability and justice together – in the context of a climate crisis (Agyeman et al. 2003; Ciplet and Harrison 2020). It is against this backdrop that a small but significant number of organisations have recently adopted a holistic food justice approach to pluralise and diversify the food politics of the possible (cf. Gibson-Graham 2006) based on the reflexive recognition that the established alterna- tive ‘local’ food movement in the UK has largely failed to critically and collectively address the structural processes that reproduce socio-environmental inequality within and beyond the food system. Indeed, addressing the multiple injustices that are inherent within the globalised, industrial, chemically-intensive food system, requires moving beyond the politics of food consumption (Agyeman and McEntee 2014) to place focus on remaking political institutions and implementing progressive policy from the ground up (Alkon and Guthman 2017). In this sense, many food activists in the UK are increasingly and strategically building connec- tions with those ‘outside’ the local food movement, par- ticularly long-standing (broadly defined) ‘left’ organising groups (such as those drawing upon socialist, green, feminist and anti-racist thought), reorienting focus away from food itself and towards issues of (in)justice, rights and sustainable livelihoods. Our research highlighted that there are multiple, situated endeavours and advocacy processes in the UK whereby the frame of food justice is a productive prism to contextualise various social movements’ activism related to food, particu- larly those who emphasise addressing class, ethnicity and/ or migrant status-based inequalities. Nevertheless, notably absent from the majority of our interviewee narratives was a reflexive consideration of the complex intersectionality of 56 H. Coulson, P. Milbourne 1 3 injustices that permeate food systems, particularly in rela- tion to (dis)ability, sexuality and race (the latter of which is central to US food justice activism; see Alkon and Agyeman 2011; Agyeman and McEntee 2014). While migrant labour was critically discussed by some interviewees who reflected upon the compounded injustices based on economic insecu- rity, gender and race/ethnicity, this was not widely discussed by members of the ‘mainstream’ local food movement. Thus, there are multiple historically-embedded invisibilities of food injustice (particularly related to workers’ rights and land ownership) in terms of how the dominant local food movement frames its priorities. This points to the erasure of the ongoing historical processes of marginalisation and disenfranchisement that reinforce distributional, recogni- tional, participative and representational injustices across the food system (Alkon and Agyeman 2011). In particular, the intersection of Brexit and the ‘crisis’ of migrant labour in the agrifood system (emphasised by some of our par- ticipants), opens up vital questions about the missing voices in deliberations of current and future UK food governance and policy, and the systems of oppression (colonialism, racism, capitalism and patriarchy) that shape post-Brexit food injustice. This requires urgent critical consideration by scholar-activists. If food justice is to act as a powerful coalescing move- ment-building framework in the UK, we suggest that culti- vating the radical and progressive edges – or the permeable boundaries – of diverse activism (that draw upon critical justice approaches) holds potential for nurturing relation- ships and developing capacity for meaningful, productive and contentious encounters across manifold creative tension points (Holt-Giménez and Shattuck 2011). Indeed, we argue seeing “the edge as an opportunity rather than a problem is more likely to be successful and adaptable” (Holmgren 2011, p. 223). In practice, this helps direct attention towards the possibilities of coalition networks to be productive trans- local assemblages that can generate connectivity between disparate established groups (such as food cooperatives, trade unions and animal welfare groups) at multiple spatial scales to facilitate shared learning and initiate or strengthen imaginative, collaborative strategies that embody a col- lective ontology of justice to work towards transformative socioecological change. Imbedding a plurivocal approach into food justice praxis by adopting a justice multiple lens highlights the unresolved tensions regarding the elasticity of the concept in terms of the trade-offs between its depth and breadth. On a practi- cal level, we are not arguing for food movement groups to incorporate all elements of the justice multiple approach within their everyday programmatic focus as this would be highly demanding and idealistic given the tension-laden ethical issues and manifold contestations that exist in rela- tion to food systems. Rather, the aim of this paper has been to propose a pluralised understanding of justice to strengthen ‘food justice’ and argue for a more inclusive, diversified and democratic food politics emanating from the UK that strives for collective solutions to structural food injustices based on shared political responsibility (Young 2011). Central to this approach is recognising the always more-than-human co-dependencies that shape food systems across space and over time. As stated above, cultivating the edges of diverse activism and advocacy to identify and nurture pluralised justice considerations holds particular promise in moving beyond pervasive dichotomies (local/global, rural/urban, human/nonhuman) in fostering avenues for broader coali- tion-building throughout the food system and beyond, based on collective solidarity to nurture food justice for all. Acknowledgements We would like to thank all our participants for generously sharing their time, thoughts and knowledge with us. We would also like to thank the two anonymous reviewers and editorial team for their helpful comments and suggestions. Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attri- bution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adapta- tion, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article’s Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article’s Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creat iveco mmons .org/licen ses/by/4.0/. References Agyeman, J., R.D. Bullard, and B. Evans. 2003. Just sustainabilities: Development in an unequal world. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Agyeman, J., and J. McEntee. 2014. Moving the field of food justice forward through the lens of urban political ecology. Geography Compass 8 (3): 211–220. Alkon, A.H. 2014. Food justice and the challenge to neoliberalism. Gastronomica 14 (2): 27–40. Alkon, A.H., and J. Agyeman (eds.). 2011. Cultivating food justice: Race, class, and sustainability. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Alkon, A.H., and J. Guthman (eds.). 2017. The new food activism: Opposition, cooperation, and collective action. Oakland, CA: University of California Press. Alkon, A.H., and T. Mares. 2012. Food sovereignty in US food move- ments: Radical visions and neoliberal constraints. Agriculture and Human Values 29 (3): 347–359. Alkon, A.H., and K.M. Norgaard. 2009. Breaking the food chains: An investigation of food justice activism. Sociological Inquiry 79 (3): 289–305. Allen, P. 2010. Realizing justice in local food systems. Cambridge Journal of Regions, Economy and Society 3 (2): 295–308. Armaline, W.T., D.S. Glasberg, and B. Purkayastha. 2015. The human rights enterprise. Cambridge: Polity Press. Barnhill, A., and T. Doggett. 2018. Food ethics I: Food production and food justice. Philosophy Compass 13 (3): 1–13. http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ 57Food justice for all?: searching for the ‘justice multiple’ in UK food movements 1 3 Baxter, B. 2005. A theory of ecological justice. New York: Routledge. Bennett, J. 2010. Vibrant matter: A political ecology of things. Durham, NC: Duke University Press. Broad, G.M. 2016. More than just food: Food justice and community change. Oakland, CA: University of California Press. Broad, G.M. 2019. Plant-based and cell-based animal product alterna- tives: An assessment and agenda for food tech justice. Geoforum 107: 223–226. Cadieux, K.V., and R. Slocum. 2015. What does it mean to do food justice? Journal of Political Ecology 22 (1): 1–26. Caney, S. 2005. Justice beyond borders: A global political theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Caney, S. 2009. Climate change and the future: Discounting for time, wealth, and risk. Journal of Social Philosophy 40 (2): 163–186. Caraher, M., and S. Furey. 2018. The economics of emergency food aid provision: A financial, social and cultural perspective. Cham: Palgrave Pivot. Ciplet, D., and J.L. Harrison. 2020. Transition tensions: Mapping con- flicts in movements for a just and sustainable transition. Environ- mental Politics 29 (3): 435–456. Clarke, J., and J. Newman. 2012. The alchemy of austerity. Critical Social Policy 32 (3): 299–319. Coole, D., and S. Frost. 2010. New materialisms: Ontology, agency and politics. Durham, NC: Duke University Press. Dieterle, J.M. (ed.). 2015. Just food: Philosophy, justice and food. London: Lanham. Dixon, B.A. 2014. Learning to see food justice. Agriculture and Human Values 31 (2): 175–184. Donaldson, S., and W. Kymlicka. 2011. Zoopolis: A political theory of animal rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Dowler, E., and H. Lambie-Mumford. 2015. How can households eat in austerity? Challenges for social policy in the UK. Social Policy and Society 14 (3): 417–428. End Hunger UK. 2019. Why end UK hunger? The case for ending hunger in the UK. Salford: Church Action on Poverty. https :// www.endhu ngeru k.org/wp-conte nt/uploa ds/2019/11/Why-End- UK-Hunge r.pdf Accessed 18 October 2019. Ferguson, H. and the Northern Rivers Landed Histories Research Group. 2016. More than something to hold the plants up: Soil as a non-human ally in the struggle for food justice. Local Environ- ment 21 (8): 956–968. Fraser, N. 1997. Justice interruptus: Critical reflections on the ‘post- socialist’ condition. New York: Routledge. Fraser, N. 2005. Reframing justice in a globalizing world. New Left Review 36: 69–88. Fraser, N. 2008. Scales of justice: Reimagining political space in a globalizing world. New York: Columbia University Press. Fraser, N., and A. Honneth. 2003. Redistribution or recognition: A political-philosophical exchange. London: Verso. Freire, P. 1970. Pedagogy of the oppressed. New York: Continuum. Garner, R. 2013. A theory of justice for animals. Oxford: Oxford Uni- versity Press. Gibson-Graham, J.K. 2006. A postcapitalist politics. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press. Glennie, C., and A.H. Alkon. 2018. Food justice: Cultivating the field. Environmental Research Letters 13 (7): 1–13. Gottlieb, R., and A. Joshi. 2010. Food justice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Guthman, J. 2008. Neoliberalism and the making of food politics in California. Geoforum 39 (3): 1171–1183. Haraway, D. 2008. When species meet. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press. Harrison, J.L. 2014. Neoliberal environmental justice: Mainstream ideas of justice in political conflict over agricultural pesticides in the United States. Environmental Politics 23 (4): 650–669. Harvey, D. 1996. Justice, nature and the geography of difference. Oxford: Blackwell. Herman, A., and M. Goodman. 2018. New spaces of food justice. Local Environment 23 (11): 1041–1046. Heynen, N., H.E. Kurtz, and A. Trauger. 2012. Food justice, hunger and the city. Geography Compass 6 (5): 304–311. Holmgren, D. 2011. Permaculture principles and pathways beyond sustainability. East Meon, Hampshire: Permanent Publications. Holt-Giménez, E. (ed.). 2011. Food movements unite!: Strategies to transform our food systems. Oakland, CA: Food First Books. Holt-Giménez, E., and A. Shattuck. 2011. Food crises, food regimes and food movements: Rumblings of reform or tides of transfor- mation? The Journal of Peasant Studies 38 (1): 109–144. Independent Working Group on Food Poverty. 2016. Dignity: End- ing hunger together in Scotland. Edinburgh: The Scottish Government. Joseph Rowntree Foundation (JRF). 2018. UK poverty 2018: A compre- hensive analysis of poverty trends and figures. Joseph Rowntree Foundation Analysis Unit. York: Joseph Rowntree Foundation. Just Fair. 2014. Going hungry? The human right to food in the UK. London: Just Fair. https ://justf air.org.uk/wp-conte nt/uploa ds/2018/05/Going -Hungr y-The-Human -Right -to-Food-in-the- UK.pdf Accessed 12 January 2019. Kneafsey, M., L. Owen, E. Bos, K. Broughton, and M. Lennarts- son. 2017. Capacity building for food justice in England: The contribution of charity-led community food initiatives. Local Environment 22 (5): 621–634. Kymlicka, W., and S. Donaldson. 2016. Locating animals in political philosophy. Philosophy Compass 11 (11): 692–701. Lang, T., D. Barling, and M. Caraher. 2009. Food policy: Integrating health, environment and society. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Latour, B. 2005. Reassembling the social: An introduction to actor- network theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Loo, C. 2014. Towards a more participative definition of food jus- tice. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 27 (5): 787–809. MacLeod, M. A. 2019. Found wanting. Understanding journeys into and out of food insecurity: A longitudinal study. A Menu for Change Report. GB: Oxfam. Mama D and C. R. Anderson. 2018. Exploring food and social justice in the UK. Breadlines: A Grassroots Journal 1(1): 1–24. https ://commu nityk nowle dgece ntred .files .wordp ress.com/2018/03/ bread lines issue -issue 1_mar19 revis ed.pdf Accessed 12 June 2019. Mares, T.M., and D.G. Peña. 2011. Environmental and food justice: Toward local, slow and deep food systems. In Cultivating food justice: Race, class, and sustainability, ed. A.H. Alkon and J. Agyeman, 197–219. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Massey, D. 1994. Space, place and gender. Cambridge: Polity Press. McClintock, N. 2014. Radical, reformist, and garden-variety neolib- eral: Coming to terms with urban agriculture’s contradictions. Local Environment 19 (2): 147–171. Millner, N. 2017. ‘The right to food is nature too’: Food justice and everyday environmental expertise in the Salvadoran permacul- ture movement. Local Environment 22 (6): 764–783. Mol, A. 2002. The body multiple: Ontology in medical practice. Durham, NC: Duke University Press. Montalvo, M.F.G. 2015. To the American food justice movements: A critique that is also an offering. Journal of Agriculture, Food Systems, and Community Development 5 (4): 125–129. Myers, J.S., and J. Sbicca. 2015. Bringing good food and good jobs: From secession to confrontation within alternative food move- ment politics. Geoforum 61: 17–26. Norrie, R. 2017. The two sides of diversity: Which are the most ethni- cally diverse occupations? London: Policy Exchange. https :// https://www.endhungeruk.org/wp-content/uploads/2019/11/Why-End-UK-Hunger.pdf https://www.endhungeruk.org/wp-content/uploads/2019/11/Why-End-UK-Hunger.pdf https://www.endhungeruk.org/wp-content/uploads/2019/11/Why-End-UK-Hunger.pdf http://justfair.org.uk/wp-content/uploads/2018/05/Going-Hungry-The-Human-Right-to-Food-in-the-UK.pdf http://justfair.org.uk/wp-content/uploads/2018/05/Going-Hungry-The-Human-Right-to-Food-in-the-UK.pdf http://justfair.org.uk/wp-content/uploads/2018/05/Going-Hungry-The-Human-Right-to-Food-in-the-UK.pdf https://communityknowledgecentred.files.wordpress.com/2018/03/breadlinesissue-issue1_mar19revised.pdf https://communityknowledgecentred.files.wordpress.com/2018/03/breadlinesissue-issue1_mar19revised.pdf https://communityknowledgecentred.files.wordpress.com/2018/03/breadlinesissue-issue1_mar19revised.pdf https://policyexchange.org.uk/wp-content/uploads/2017/03/The-two-sides-of-diversity-2.pdf 58 H. Coulson, P. Milbourne 1 3 polic yexch ange.org.uk/wp-conte nt/uploa ds/2017/03/The-two- sides -of-diver sity-2.pdf Accessed 12 April 2019. Nourish Scotland and the Poverty Truth Commission. 2018. Dignity in practice. Scotland, UK: Nourish. Nussbaum, M. 2000. Women and human development: The capabili- ties approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Nussbaum, M. 2006. Frontiers of justice: Disability, nationality, spe- cies membership. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. O’Hara, M. 2014. Austerity bites. Bristol: Policy Press. Paddock, J. 2016. Positioning food cultures: ‘Alternative’ food as distinctive consumer practice. Sociology 50 (6): 1039–1055. Parfit, D. [1984] 2004. Justice across generations: The non-identity problem. In Social Justice, eds. W. Clayton and A. Williams, 286–308. Oxford: Blackwell. Pellow, D.N. 2014. Total liberation: The power and promise of ani- mal rights and the radical earth movement. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press. Penniman, L. 2018. Farming while Black: Soul Fire Farm’s practi- cal guide to liberation on the land. White River Junction, VT: Chelsea Green Publishing. Pepper, A. 2016. Beyond anthropocentrism: Cosmopolitanism and nonhuman animals. Global Justice: Theory, Practice, Rhetoric 9 (2): 114–133. Perz, S.G., H. Covington, J.E. Moscoso, L. Griffin, G. Jacobson, F. Leite, A. Mook, C. Overdevest, T.G. Samuels-Jones, and R. Thomson. 2018. Future direction for application of political economy in environmental and resource sociology: Selected research priorities going forward. Environmental Sociology 4 (4): 470–487. Plumwood, V. 2001. Nature as agency and the prospects for a progres- sive naturalism. Capitalism Nature Socialism 12 (4): 3–32. Plunkett, D. 2016. Justice, non-human animals, and the methodology of political philosophy. Jurisprudence 7 (1): 1–29. Pogge, T. 1989. Realizing Rawls. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Pogge, T. 2002. World poverty and human rights: Cosmopolitan responsibilities and reforms. Cambridge: Polity. Poppendieck, J. 1998. Sweet charity? Emergency food and the end of entitlement. New York: Viking. Raj, K. 2019. Nothing left in the cupboards: Austerity, welfare cuts, and the right to food in the UK. London: Human Rights Watch. https ://www.hrw.org/sites /defau lt/files /repor t_pdf/uk051 9_web3. pdf Accessed 14 June 2019. Rawls, J. 1971. A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press. Reynolds, K., and N. Cohen. 2016. Beyond the kale: Urban agriculture and social justice activism in New York City. Athens, GA: The University of Georgia Press. Rodríguez, S. (ed.). 2018. Food justice: A primer. Wroclaw: Sanctuary Publishers. Sbicca, J. 2012. Growing food justice by planting an anti-oppression foundation: Opportunities and obstacles for a budding social movement. Agriculture and Human Values 29 (4): 455–466. Sbicca, J. 2018. Food justice now!: Deepening the roots of social strug- gle. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press. Schlosberg, D. 2007. Defining environmental justice. New York: Oxford University Press. Schuppert, F. 2011. Climate change mitigation and intergenerational justice. Environmental Politics 20 (3): 303–321. Sen, A. 1999. Commodities and capabilities. Oxford: Oxford Univer- sity Press. Sen, A. 2009. The idea of justice. London: Allen Lane. Singer, P. 1975. Animal liberation. New York: Harper. Slocum, R. 2018. Must everything be called ‘food justice’? Local Envi- ronment 23 (11): 1103–1105. Slocum, R., K.V. Cadieux, and R. Blumberg. 2016. Solidarity, space, and race: Toward geographies of agrifood justice. Justice Spa- tiale / Spatial Justice 9: 1–34. Soja, E.W. 2010. Seeking spatial justice. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press. Sutton, J. 2016. Food worth fighting for: From food riots to food banks. London: Prospect Books. Thiemann, L., and A. Roman-Alcalá. 2019. Fast food sovereignty: Con- tradiction in terms or logical next step? Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 32 (5–6): 813–834. Tornaghi, C. 2016. Urban agriculture in the food-disabling city: (Re) defining urban food justice, reimagining a politics of empower- ment. Antipode 49 (3): 781–801. Twine, R. 2012. Revealing the ‘animal-industrial complex’ – A concept & method for critical animal studies. Journal for Critical Animal Studies 10 (1): 12–39. Walker, G. 2009. Beyond distribution and proximity: Exploring the multiple spatialities of environmental justice. Antipode 41 (4): 614–636. Williams, A., P. Cloke, J. May, and M. Goodwin. 2016. Contested space: The contradictory political dynamics of food banking in the UK. Environment and Planning A 48 (11): 2291–2316. Young, I.M. 1990. Justice and the politics of difference. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Young, I.M. 2011. Responsibility for justice. Oxford: Oxford Univer- sity Press. Publisher’s Note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. Helen Coulson is a Lecturer in Human Geography and Planning (Food) in the School of Geography and Planning at Cardiff University. As a political ecologist, her research focuses on the role of governance, power and (in)justice in relation to food systems. Her current research centres on the geographies of ethics and justice in developing translocal care-full food justice politics. Paul Milbourne is Professor of Human Geography in the School of Geography and Planning at Cardiff University and Director of the University’s Centre for Research on Environment, Society and Space. His main research interests lie in the field of social geography, and, more specifically, the geographies of welfare and poverty. Paul is also interested in environmental geographies, particularly the interplay between social and environmental forms of injustice within contem- porary society. His current research projects are concerned with urban food systems, food justice, urban agriculture and migrant workers in the agri-food system. https://policyexchange.org.uk/wp-content/uploads/2017/03/The-two-sides-of-diversity-2.pdf https://policyexchange.org.uk/wp-content/uploads/2017/03/The-two-sides-of-diversity-2.pdf https://www.hrw.org/sites/default/files/report_pdf/uk0519_web3.pdf https://www.hrw.org/sites/default/files/report_pdf/uk0519_web3.pdf Food justice for all?: searching for the ‘justice multiple’ in UK food movements Abstract Introduction Interrogating political theories of ‘justice’ in food justice Pluralising justice: distribution, recognition, participation and enhancing capabilities Expanding justice across space and time: global duties, obligations to distant others and intergenerational rights Extending justice to the more-than-human: posthuman social justice and nonhuman vitality Researching conceptualisations of justice in UK food movements Examining justice in UK food movements Pluralising justice through rights-based approaches to food Enacting sociospatial (food) justice: labour rights, consumptive politics and the invisibility of workers Transforming food systems through socioecological justice: extending justice to the more-than-human The justice multiple in UK food movements Acknowledgements References work_5lttov63fvhbzmzs2em4berfqa ---- Disability: a justice-based account Disability: a justice-based account Jessica Begon1 Published online: 18 May 2020 � The Author(s) 2020 Abstract Most people have a clear sense of what they mean by disability, and have little trouble identifying conditions they consider disabling. Yet providing a clear and consistent definition of disability is far from straightforward. Standardly, dis- ability is understood as the restriction in our abilities to perform tasks, as a result of an impairment of normal physical or cognitive human functioning (in combination with our social, political, and environmental context, and our resource share). However, which inabilities matter? We are all restricted by our bodies, and are all incapable of performing some tasks, but most of these inabilities are not considered disabilities. If, then, we are to avoid the category of disability becoming overly broad—and thus politically and practically useless—we need some way of picking out the specific inabilities that are disabling. I argue that our answer should be informed by an account of the opportunities individuals are entitled to be able to perform as a matter of justice. Thus, to be disabled is to have these opportunities restricted, and not to deviate from the species norm or lack any ability that might improve our well-being. Keywords Disability � Impairment � Distributive justice � Well-being � Species functioning & Jessica Begon jessica.e.begon@durham.ac.uk 1 School of Government and International Affairs, Durham University, The Al-Qasimi Building, Elvet Hill Rd, Durham DH1 3TU, UK 123 Philos Stud (2021) 178:935–962 https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-020-01466-3 http://orcid.org/0000-0002-2701-4272 http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1007/s11098-020-01466-3&domain=pdf https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-020-01466-3 1 The problem of defining disability My goal is to defend a new account of disability: one that is indexed to an account of distributive justice, or what individuals are entitled to. Yet it may seem that determining how disability should be defined needs no further investigation. Most people have a clear sense of which conditions they consider disabling. Further, there is broad philosophical consensus on some central features of an account of disability. First, there is a widely accepted distinction between impairment as physical or cognitive features that cause deviation from a biological or statistical norm of species functioning, and disability as a restriction in our ability to perform tasks. 1 There is considerable agreement, too, that disability is caused in part by impairment, and in part by an individual’s social and political context, and the resources they have access to. 2 I do not intend to challenge the consensus on either point. Rather, I ask: if disability is the restriction in our ability to perform tasks, then which inabilities matter? In other words, which of the limitations that result from individuals’ impairments, in combination with their context and resources, should be considered disabling? We are all restricted by our bodies, and are all incapable of performing some tasks, but most of these inabilities are not considered disabilities. An account of disability is an essential prerequisite to formulating public policies that safeguard the just treatment of disabled individuals, and an account cannot form the basis of such policy if it simply concludes that ‘everyone is disabled’. If, then, we are to avoid the category of disability becoming overly broad—and thus politically and practically useless—we need some way of picking out which inabilities are relevant to defining disability. Only then can we identify and respond to the injustice, discrimination, and mistreatment to which so many disabled individuals are subject. I begin, in Sect. 2, by considering and rejecting alternative accounts of which inabilities are disabling: those entailed by ‘normal’ species functioning (Buchanan et al. 2000; Daniels 1985), those that undermine well-being (Kahane and Savulescu 2009; Savulescu and Kahane 2009), and those considered relevant by disability activists (Barnes 2016a). I demonstrate that the latter approach leaves disability underspecified, whilst on the former two approaches disability will be ubiquitous. As such, all of these alternatives prove an inadequate basis for public policy, political campaigning, or activist movements. I argue, instead, that the relevant opportunity losses involve restrictions of individuals’ entitlements (Sect. 3). Thus, I define disability as the restriction in the ability to perform those tasks human beings 1 For example: Terzi (2004), Nussbaum (2006), Shakespeare (2006), Smith (2001), Buchanan et al. (2000), Oliver (1996). Though some recent work questions this distinction (Barnes 2018, 2016a). 2 In other words, we should reject both a strict medical model of disability (according to which disability is straightforwardly caused by individual impairment), and a strict social model (which denies this causal relationship, insisting instead that disability is solely the result of unjust social structures). Whilst social structures can certainly be disabling, it is also clear that disability could not be eliminated by social changes alone (Barclay 2010: 161; Shakespeare 2006: 46; Terzi 2004). Hence, we should adopt a hybrid account, which acknowledges the influence of social factors, without ignoring the impact of impairment (for example, Wolff 2009a; Kahane and Savulescu 2009; Shakespeare 2006; Terzi 2008; Daniels et al. 2009). 936 J. Begon 123 are entitled to be able to perform as a matter of justice, as the result of the interaction between an individual’s impairment, their social and political context, and the resources they have available to them. This provides a framework account of disability. To determine whether an impairment is actually disabling will require an account of our distributive entitlements, but this is not a prerequisite to accepting the general claim that individuals are disabled when their access to these entitlements is restricted (as a result of their impairment and context). (As subsequent discussions will illustrate, the case of disability does give us some reason to favour particular accounts of distributive justice over others, but I will not attempt to mount a definitive defence of one particular approach here.) In Sect. 4 I consider some possible objections to the definition I have sketched. First, it may seem that if being disabled means lacking what we are entitled to, then in cases where this cannot be rectified, this cannot be unjust. This implies individuals with serious impairments would not be considered disabled on my account. Second, in part to avoid the former objection, I adopt a broadly-specified and multiply-realisable conception of entitlements: for example, as opportunities for mobility, communication, or forming relationships. This leaves me vulnerable to the further worry that individuals will not be considered disabled, or entitled to assistance, even when unable to perform important functionings (walking, hearing, easily reading social cues) if they have more general capabilities in these domains. I respond to these objections in Sects. 5 and 6. I finish, in Sect. 7, by considering the revisionary and counterintuitive implications of my account. It will, for example, imply that individuals with significant and visible impairments may not be disabled by them, that individuals with apparently minor or invisible impairments may be disabled, and that individuals’ status as disabled may change across time and context. However, I argue that far from giving us a reason to reject my approach, this is one its key benefits. The intuitions with which this approach may clash ought to be challenged: our understanding of disability should no longer focus on bodily difference or deviation from what we take to be the norm, and should instead reflect a concern with the opportunities that all individuals ought to have access to, and which are closed to so many. 2 What disability is not 2.1 Disability and impairment In this section I outline and critique alternative accounts of disability. However, I do not challenge the distinction between disability and impairment, or the consensus that the cause of disability involves both individual impairment and wider context. This terminology is worth clarifying. Impairment can be understood as ‘‘departure from human normality’’ (Terzi 2008: 43) or atypical forms of physical or cognitive functioning, and might include blindness, deafness, and mobility impairments, as well as non-standard cognitive functionings experienced by individuals with autistic spectrum conditions (ASCs), Down’s syndrome, or Alzheimer’s. Disabilities are the Disability: a justice-based account 937 123 ‘‘activity limitations, and participation restrictions’’ that may result (WHO 2017). There are various views on which such limitations are disabling. For example, those who subscribe to a species norm approach deem the relevant functioning restrictions to be those ‘‘that individuals in someone’s reference group (e.g. adults) are ordinarily able to do’’ (Buchanan et al. 2000: 286). The goal of the paper is to defend a different approach. Distinguishing disability and impairment draws attention to the contingency of the connection between bodily and cognitive difference and having a disability, which also depends on context, resources, and personal features. Indeed, highlighting this contingency was a major motivation behind the development of the social model by the disability rights movement. 3 Further, as we will see, this distinction both allows us to campaign against disability, as restriction, without suggesting that we should seek to normalise human bodies and minds by eliminating impairments, and enables us to describe the shared experience of atypical functioning of those who have an impairment, whether they are disabled by it or not. Nonetheless, objections may be raised against this terminology. First, whilst common among disability scholars and activists, outside this community this language might strike some as clumsy and counterintuitive. We are very used to calling people with impairments—of vision, mobility, cognitive function—disabled, without paying much attention to the restrictions in activity or participation they may or may not face. It may seem awkward to insist that an individual in a wheelchair—often the literal poster-child of disability—is merely impaired, and that this might not translate into a disability. Yet this discomfort is often grounded in the unexamined assumption that differences in physical and cognitive functionings must manifest themselves in restrictions of ability, and the associated belief that the impaired body or mind is, itself, the problem. These intuitions, however strong, ought to be questioned, as the disability rights movement has long argued. A second, more serious worry concerns the potential normative implications of labelling individuals ‘impaired’. This is not intended to be an evaluative concept. It simply provides a way of distinguishing disability, which (partially) results from impairment, from other forms of disadvantage, such as that associated with some racial or gender identities, or sexual orientation. 4 Further, (almost) everyone in some way deviates from the norm; hence, has an impairment. Nonetheless, this term has connotations of deficiency, defect, and imperfection. It may, therefore, seem more 3 The social model not only drew a conceptual distinction between impairment and disability, but, in some iterations, disputed the causal connection between them (see fn.2). 4 This is in addition to the other noted benefits: highlighting both the contingency of the connection between impairment and disadvantage, and the shared experience of atypical functioning. A further reason to accept this distinction is that I am not convinced by the arguments of its primary opponent— Barnes (2016a: 23–28, 2018)—for its rejection. Briefly, these are: first, that our judgements about who is impaired rely on our intuitions about disability, and that there is no distinct explanatorily and extensionally adequate account of impairment; and, second, that this will lead to an overly disembodied view of disability focussing merely on social exclusion and ignoring the ‘‘messy reality’’ of having a disabled body (Barnes 2018: 1158). I believe these claims can best be refuted with a neutral account of impairment, though I cannot rehearse these arguments here (see Begon (unpublished).) For further critiques of Barnes’s view of impairment, see Howard and Aas (2018) and Francis (2018). 938 J. Begon 123 apt to refer to ‘difference’, ‘diversity’, or ‘heterogeneity’. I do not do so only to avoid the proliferation of competing terminology. However, to emphasise, impairment is synonymous with difference rather than deficiency. Yet this neutral account of impairment may seem to leave my approach vulnerable to a third objection: that it will render the category of disability over- inclusive. As noted, part of the reason to accept the standard distinction between disability and impairment is that this helps to distinguish disability from other forms of socially-mediated disadvantage. However, if impairment implies mere atypicality (rather than deficiency) then it may still seem to include almost everyone: even individuals with better than normal functioning may count as impaired, in obvious tension with its usual meaning. The most straightforward response here is to note that accepting my general account of disability does not hang on accepting this view of impairment. It is possible to agree that individuals are disabled when they lack the opportunities they are entitled to, though to focus on cases in which this results from functioning in a ‘deficient’ or ‘unhealthy’ way. More substantively, I believe both that there are positive reasons to adopt a neutral account of impairment, and that this will not render disability problemat- ically over-inclusive, though I lack the space to fully defend either claim here. 5 To briefly tackle the over-inclusiveness worry: first, it is true that better functioning individuals will count as impaired (assuming functionings can meaningfully be described as simply ‘better’, as opposed to better suited to a particular context). However, describing Michael Phelps (to take Barnes’s (2016a: 14–15) oft-cited example) as impaired is hardly implausible if this just means he functions atypically. The important question is whether he is disabled—whether he lacks opportunities he is entitled to—and it is clear that he is not. A broad account of impairment does not necessitate a broad account of disability, then. Second, racial identity and sexual orientation will not count as impairments insofar as racial 5 See Begon (unpublished). In brief support of the neutral approach: first, it avoids the implication that the appropriate response to impairment must be to cure or eliminate it, which seems to follow if impairment is taken to imply deficiency or ill-health. Second, it avoids the difficult task of determining which ways of functioning are non-contextually worse: whilst certain forms of physical and cognitive functioning do not fit well with some environmental contexts it is far from straightforward to identify a principle that determines which deviations from the norm are simply negative. Finally, the neutral approach provides a means of responding to a worry that might be raised about under-inclusiveness: if impairment is deficiency then those whose functioning cannot plausibly be described as deficient, such as some autistic persons, will not be considered disabled. One means of avoiding such exclusion is to allow that individuals may be disabled if they are merely perceived as, or treated as if, they are impaired [indeed, the ADA has taken this approach (see Francis 2018 for discussion), and for a defence of this position see Aas (2016) and Howard and Aas (2018)]. This move is unnecessary if impairment merely implies difference: these individuals straightforwardly count as impaired insofar as their functioning is atypical, and are disabled if they lack opportunities they are entitled to. No claim about deficiency is necessary. Thus, we need not attempt the thorny challenge of formulating an account of deficiency. Nor need we distinguish those in the disabled community who are ‘really’ impaired (i.e. defective) and those who are wrongly perceived as such. For further arguments against this approach see Begon (unpublished). However, it is worth emphasising that accepting the central claim of this paper does not demand acceptance of these arguments: perhaps individuals are disabled when they lack the opportunities they are entitled to as a result of being perceived to function in a deficient (or, indeed, merely atypical) way. Disability: a justice-based account 939 123 phenotypes and preferences cannot plausibly be described as functionings. 6 Sex- based differences may seem to present a harder case since there do seem to be differences in the functional capacities of average male and female-bodied persons, most obviously (though not only) relating to differences in their reproductive capacities. We do not need to accept the existence of a strict binary, or a metaphysically deep reason to appeal to reference classes based on sex categories, to allow that our assessment of typical functionings can be indexed to the capacities of biological females and males. Thus, a male is not impaired by their inability to bear young. 7 A neutral account of impairment, then, need not lead to the inclusion of other forms of disadvantage in the category of disability. 2.2 Species norm accounts I therefore accept the distinction between disability and impairment, where the latter concept will make some reference to normal species functioning, but nonetheless reject accounts where disability itself comprises the loss of species-normal abilities. The most obvious worry is that these accounts will be over-inclusive since individuals depart from the species norm in many trivial (or even beneficial) ways. Raising an eyebrow might be a species-normal ability, but those who lack it surely are not disabled. Allen Buchanan et al. (2000: 285) attempt to avoid this problem by distinguishing ‘‘impairment of normal species functioning’’ from disability as the resulting inability to perform a significant range of tasks. To illustrate, they consider someone who cannot hear sound at a particular range of frequencies, yet in whose environment nothing ‘‘she is likely to be required to do or would benefit from doing’’ requires hearing sound in this range (Buchanan et al. 2000: 287). This individual thus has an impairment, but this does not translate into a disability. 6 I assume that preferences and appearance do not constitute ways of functioning though they may be functional, but I lack the space to defend this view. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for raising this point. 7 It might seem that trans persons are a difficult case to accommodate here. Whilst I cannot attempt a full account of this complex and controversial topic, it is not immediately obvious that this must be so. Roughly I would suggest, first, that either conforming to, or subverting, socially-constructed gendered behaviours should not be considered a form of physical or cognitive functioning, but a preference about how to live our lives. Thus, individuals whose gender presentation is non-binary or does not conform to their assigned sex should not be understood as having an atypical functioning capacity. Second, individuals who change their sex identity or change their body to corresponded to their true sex might be impaired if they are unable to perform functionings that are typical for this sex. For example, trans women who are unable to bear young or menstruate could be said to function atypically, and could potentially be disabled too, depending on the consequences of such restrictions, just as natal women who cannot so function might be. This does not imply that there is anything pathological about mere possession of a trans identity, thus following the DSM-5 (2013) in accepting that ‘‘gender nonconformity is not itself a mental disorder’’. {I leave aside, here, the question of whether there may nonetheless be reasons for trans persons to choose to adopt a disabled status if this is the only way to ensure their rights are protected [as Wahlert and Gill (2017) argue]}. This would not hold true if we do not believe individuals can choose or change their sex, in which case these trans women would be normal functioning male-bodied persons with female gender identity and presentation—and thus not impaired. I take no view on which approach is correct, but merely sketch how they may be accommodated. For further discussion of these issues see, for example, Bettcher (2014a, b), Dembroff (forthcoming), Jenkins (2016). 940 J. Begon 123 However, this distinction between inabilities to perform species-normal functionings and species-normal tasks is difficult to draw—at least, without some additional account of which of these tasks are ‘significant’. Indeed, in describing their example, Buchanan et al. (2000: 287) make reference to what we might ‘‘be required’’ to do or ‘‘would benefit’’ from doing. By (implicitly) drawing on these ideas they can avoid the inclusion of trivial inabilities. However, this also suggests that their means of identifying relevant restrictions is not purely based on a species norm, and so is no longer a species norm approach. Furthermore, this approach’s focus on ‘tasks’ may mean it is under-inclusive. Consider, for example, individuals who suffer from chronic pain, anxiety, or depression, but who are nonetheless high-functioning and able to perform all species-normal tasks (or those they are required to do, or that benefit them). These cases are analogous to the individual who cannot hear particular sound frequencies: they may not function as normal, but this does not translate into a restriction in their abilities. Yet it is implausible to suggest that individuals who struggle with pain, anxiety, and depression are not disabled until this manifests in an inability to perform tasks. Buchanan et al. could respond by adopting a more expansive understanding of tasks, and thus of disability. They might point out that performing tasks whilst suffering is not species-normal: we should not focus just on what people can achieve but on whether their method of achievement is normal. This response would, indeed, allow them to include individuals with chronic pain, depression, and so on, but would seem to come at the cost of also including their hearing-impaired person, and other trivial cases. After all, the species-normal way of performing the task of hearing includes, inter alia, not being in pain and hearing sound frequencies within a certain range. This fully inclusive approach is both implausible and contrary to their stated view. The route out would involve an appeal to which of the atypical ways of achieving a task are relevant or significant and this, as noted, takes us beyond the appeal to mere species norms. (As Sect. 6 will consider, this route is open to me since I am explicitly committed to a principle that identifies which of the various ways of performing atypical functionings are disabling.) Accepting an account of impairment grounded in species norms does not raise the problems that plague this approach to disability. First, impairment should be an expansive category. Thus, we need not resist the inclusion of the individual with the mild hearing impairment, and those with anxiety, depression, and chronic pain—and even those who cannot raise an eyebrow, or Michael Phelps. This does not imply that disability must be similarly all-encompassing since, unlike Buchanan et al., I explicitly offer a criterion to identify which of the associated restrictions are disabling. Second, if impairment is normatively neutral—synonymous with difference, not defect—it is not vulnerable to a final objection often raised against species norm accounts of disability. This is the worry that focussing on an idealised conception of normal species functioning entails a corresponding disrespect of, and insult to, those who fail to meet this ideal. For example: the whole ideology of normal functioning is seen as primarily constructed…to control and exclude disabled people from active and full participation in social Disability: a justice-based account 941 123 and institutional arrangements which have no interest in accommodating them. (Terzi 2009: 90) An account of impairment that is indexed to species norms merely acknowledges that many (or all) of us are not ‘normal’ in various ways and, whilst not problematic in itself, this can, in some circumstances, prevent us from having the opportunities we are entitled to. The same can be said of gender and racial identities and sexual orientation without implying any such identity is deficient. 2.3 Welfarist accounts The second account of disability I will consider is the welfarist approach. This is most clearly and explicitly defined and defended by Kahane and Savulescu (2009: 53), according to whom disability is a: stable physical or psychological property of subject S that tends to reduce S’s level of well-being in circumstances C, when contrasted with a realistic alternative, excluding the effect that this condition has on well-being that is due to prejudice against S. Thus, the relevant inabilities, on this view, are those that reduce welfare. Perhaps the most obvious problem with this account concerns the difficulties in developing an account of welfare. Whilst Kahane and Savulescu aim to remain neutral between alternative accounts, there are problems with any that might be incorporated. This reflects the more general difficulties with formulating a clear and satisfactory account of welfare, which cannot be rehearsed here. 8 However, in brief: first, a subjective account of welfare, relying on the individuals’ self-assessment, will inevitably raise reliability concerns. The various ways in which self-reported levels of happiness, contentment, or preference-satisfaction, can be misleading have been well-documented. 9 Yet moving toward a more objective understanding of welfare brings its own problems. For example, the difficulty of finding a non- arbitrary way of compiling a list of basic goods, or the worry that this list will entail the paternalist imposition of a perfectionist conception of the good, or that it will be elitist and exclusionary. Further, we may be sceptical about the implication that something can be considered good for someone independently of their attitudes towards it, and indeed, despite their own insistence to the contrary. A further problem in the social justice context is the epistemic difficulty of assessing welfare in many cases. For example, Kahane and Savulescu (2009) discuss the ‘Ashley treatment’, named after a child with severe cognitive impairments who was given treatment to restrict her further growth and prevent puberty. They argue that though this treatment moved Ashley further from the species norm, it lessened her disability since it improved her welfare. This stands in stark contrast to, for example, Eva Feder Kittay’s discussion of the case, in part 8 Some of the many contributions to this debate include: Scanlon (1975, 1998), Griffin (1986), Crisp (2006), Sumner (1996), Parfit (1984). 9 For example, Kahneman et al. (1982), Elster (1987), Khader ( 2011). 942 J. Begon 123 because Kittay employs a different understanding of Ashley’s welfare. She contends that ‘‘[w]e take pleasure and pride in our bodies as they grow and mature because…we do. Full stop. It needs no further justification. It is constitutive of a thriving life’’ (Kittay 2011: 621). Yet evidently Kahane and Savluescu do not recognise this value. These epistemic difficulties are especially intractable in cases such as Ashley’s where it can be hard to ascertain the view of the individual concerned, and far from clear that those who have not experienced this condition can understand what would be required for her to thrive. Thus, Kahane and Savulescu’s definition does not determine who is disabled, but simply moves the debate to a new context: finding a satisfactory account of welfare. This is an important gap in their approach. However, the fact they have not filled it does not mean it cannot be satisfactorily filled (though given how long this debate has raged, scepticism regarding its speedy resolution seems justified). Further, a welfarist might respond that disability should not be easy to define, and that my own approach will face similar worries—there is, of course, no consensus on what justice demands. However, these epistemic worries are, perhaps, deeper for welfarist approaches—at least for those that include an element of subjectivity in their account of welfare—since they necessarily require a direct reliance on first person testimony. Moreover, whilst we may not have reached agreement on a complete theory of justice, it might be easier to agree on basic entitlements and so basic injustices than it is to identify core instances of welfare deficit. Further, we may need to agree on certain essentials of a theory of justice, unlike welfare, if we are to determine how the benefits and burdens of social cooperation are to be distributed (Rawls 1999: 5). For example, it is, perhaps, easier to agree that individuals are entitled to equal political participation, opportunities for mobility, and the ability to form relationships than it is to show that all these capabilities will make all individuals better-off, given the existence of the idiosyncratic preferences of the politically apathetic, sedentary, and misanthropic. Thus, disagreements about what makes life go well may be harder to settle even in apparently core cases, as examples like Ashley illustrate. Yet welfarists could doubtless disagree. As such, noting the lack of a widely-accepted account of welfare raises a worry that demands a response, rather than providing a decisive refutation of the welfarist view. The deeper problem for this view is that, whatever account of welfare is used, disability will be ubiquitous, and this will prove problematic from the perspective of justice and public policy. As Kahane and Savulescu (2009: 30) openly acknowl- edge, disability will be a degree rather than a threshold concept. Thus, ‘‘everyone has disabilities of one kind or another’’. 10 I agree that there can be a degree of 10 Arguably, Terzi’s (2008, 2009) approach could also be included as welfarist. Terzi adopts a capability approach to disability, and so understands impairments as disabling insofar as they cause a loss of, or restriction in, capabilities. However, she understands the capability approach as an account of subjective well-being, and so considers the loss of capabilities to entail the loss of components of well-being. Thus, individuals are disabled by capability loss because this renders them worse off. For example, she suggests that whether a wheelchair user has a capability depends on her ‘‘most valuable ends’’ and her ‘‘attitude’’ (Terzi 2009: 99): if these are such that she cannot fulfil her goals as the result of being in a wheelchair ‘‘her well-being appears to be restricted…and hence the full set of capabilities available to this person is diminished’’ (Terzi 2009: 100). If we interpret Terzi as implying individuals are disabled whenever their Disability: a justice-based account 943 123 arbitrariness in determining the boundaries of disability. I agree, too, that we have reasons to expand this category (as Sect. 7 discusses). Nonetheless, we should be cautious of expanding it so far that it becomes meaningless, as it will be if it is a category in which everyone is included. If every stable physical or psychological property that lowers our welfare counts as disabling, then this definition does not seem to pick out the right cases—or, not only the right cases. At least, not in the context of social justice, where our concern is identifying disadvantage and determining how the state should appropriately respond. It is certainly worth emphasising that disability is a continuum, and that we are all restricted by the limitations of our bodies and minds. Nonetheless, when fighting against ableism and injustice, simply concluding that ‘we are all disabled’ is unhelpful. Similarly, we may wish to reject binaries of sexual orientation and gender identity, and deny that racial categorisation is possible, yet nonetheless find it useful to refer to ‘women’, and ‘gay people’, and ‘black people’ as a means of identifying, and fighting against, injustices against these groups. ‘Disability’, I contend, has value and meaning as a way of identifying, and responding to, disadvantage. The term has little function if entirely ubiquitous. 11 2.4 Barnes’s social constructionist approach Barnes, like many others, rejects the social model’s exclusive focus on external causes of disability, and emphasises that our understanding of disability should be grounded in an assessment of individuals’ physical features—or, ‘‘what their body is (really) like’’ (Barnes 2016a: 38). 12 However, she also emphasises that particular qualities are considered significant not because of their objective features, but because of how we think about them. Barnes further argues that those best placed to determine which features should be considered disabling are disability activists. Thus, ‘‘disability just is whatever the disability rights movement is promoting justice for’’ (Barnes 2016a: 43). Inclusion in the category of disability therefore depends on ‘‘rule-based solidarity among people with certain kinds of bodies’’ (Barnes 2016a: 46). However, there may be problems with relying on such rules. First, we should not unquestioningly accept the content of these rules. Whilst disabled individuals’ testimony should undoubtedly play an important role in developing an account of disability, it does not follow that the rules adopted by the disability rights movement will be free of bias. Individuals who already ‘count’ as disabled may have vested interests in excluding others from entering this group, and perhaps diluting the strength of their claims with the accretion of many others. This need not be a Footnote 10 continued well-being is restricted and capabilities diminished as a result of an impairment, then disability would also be ubiquitous on her account. 11 Further, though we do not want to replicate a common-sense understanding of disability, it should not be entirely divorced from our intuitions. Indeed, Kahane and Savluescu (2009: 19) themselves object to the species norm approach on this basis. 12 Barnes discusses only physical, and not cognitive, disabilities. 944 J. Begon 123 conscious process of exclusion. Individuals may simply tend to see their own impairments as the paradigm, and be less inclined to include those they are less familiar with. Thus, we should not assume that disabled individuals’ epistemically privileged position regarding their own experience extends to understanding the diverse experiences of all disabled people. 13 Nor can we assume that a group fighting against injustice will never unjustly exclude others. Consider, for example, the exclusion of asexual individuals by some in the LGBTQ ? community, or the exclusion of trans women by some feminists. The point is not that such exclusion is unjust, but that the question is not resolved by observing that existing members of the community determined these boundaries. 14 A related worry is that, given the heterogeneity that exists between and within such groups, disagreement about the content and application of the rules of inclusion seems likely, and difficult to resolve. Barnes (2016a: 49) acknowledges the diversity of disability rights movements, and allows that it may be ‘‘simply vague or indeterminate which social group is referred to…[as] ‘the disability rights movement’’’. Her response is to insist that ‘‘this entire domain…is riddled with indeterminacy’’ (Barnes 2016a: 49), and that it would be ‘‘deeply implausible’’ if it turned out that ‘‘any aspect of our complex, multifaceted social reality had fully determinate boundaries’’ (Barnes 2016a: 50). It is true that any definition will likely include borderline cases. Indeed, an account that provides a firm and unequivocal distinction seems to have missed something important about the category of disability. Yet even if the boundaries are somewhat indeterminate, we still need some sense of where they lie, and I am sceptical that the implicit rules used by disability rights movements will be sufficient for this task. 15 Further, I believe there are deeper flaws in Barnes’s approach, which can be seen by considering two criteria Barnes (2016a: 10–13) sets out for a successful account of disability: first, that it should not prejudge normative issues and, second, that it should deliver the correct verdict about paradigm cases. These criteria will not be met by my account, but I contend that an account of disability need not—and, indeed, should not attempt to—fulfil these criteria. Considering the latter first, it is not clear why it would be a virtue of an account to be ‘correct’ about paradigm cases. Whilst we may worry about an approach that bears no relation to our understanding of disability—for example, an account that includes homosexuality— we should also be aware that our sense of the ‘paradigm’ is often informed by intuitions that are based on prejudice about, and misunderstanding of, disabled lives. 16 As noted, these worries may not be solved by allowing those who are already considered part of this ‘paradigm’ to be the arbiters of who else will be included. 13 For a discussion of the impact of restricted information on the reliability of individuals’ choices and preferences see Begon (2018a). 14 Similar worries are raised by Campbell and Stramondo (2016), Wasserman (2018), and Howard and Aas (2018: 1127). 15 Also see: Wasserman (2018: 254), Howard and Aas (2018: 1115), Francis (2018). 16 As Sect. 7 considers and Barnes (2016a: 119–142, 2009) herself has pointed out. Disability: a justice-based account 945 123 Next, Barnes (2016a: 11) insists that ‘‘[i]t should not be built into the very definition of disability that disability is something that’s bad or suboptimal’’. However, it is only important that disability be value-neutral if we follow Barnes in rejecting the distinction between impairment and disability. 17 If we accept this distinction, we can allow that disability is necessarily disadvantageous and still maintain a normatively neutral account of impairment, capturing the heterogeneity of human bodies and capacities, which may be disadvantageous in some contexts but need not be so. This does not undermine the possibility of being proud of our diverse bodies and minds. However, conflating these terms makes it near impossible to achieve the twin goals of recognising that diversity need not be negative, and that it can be correlated with disadvantage, which must be identified to be rectified. Barnes meets her own criteria, and so argues that disability is a ‘mere difference’. Yet this does not mean it has no effect on individuals’ lives. On the contrary, it ‘‘may be good for you, it may be bad for you, it may be utterly indifferent for you’’ (Barnes 2016a: 98). Indeed, Barnes allows that being disabled may sometimes lower overall well-being, that some aspects of some disabilities are bad-differences (Barnes 2016a: 75), and even that some specific disabilities are bad simpliciter [something that makes ‘‘your life go worse in virtue of it specifically’’ (Barnes 2016a: 87; 102)]. By including diverse conditions within this wider category, it becomes true that disability is not necessarily a bad-difference, but this category still encompasses conditions (whether few or many) that are bad-differences.18 Clearly, then, Barnes does not believe that ‘‘the positive effects [of disability] have to balance the negative ones’’, and accepts that ‘‘in the world we inhabit, disability tends to significantly reduce one’s good options’’—contra the claims of some of her critics (Kahane and Savulescu 2016: 777, 776). 19 Nonetheless, espousing a ‘value-neutral model’ or ‘mere-difference view’ of disability can be importantly misleading, especially if this is used to ground general claims about the kinds of policies that should be pursued with regards to disability. Certainly we should acknowledge that it is ‘‘simply untrue that, as a general rule, disabilities are bad for those who have them’’ (Campbell and Stramondo 2017: 176). Thus, claims rooted in the general assumption that someone’s life will be worse simply because they have ‘a disability’ are unjustified. 20 However, we should also avoid grounding claims about policy on the assumption that all disabilities should be treated as neutral simply because this category incorporates conditions with good, bad, and neutral effects. For example, we may accept that disability is a mere-difference in Barnes’s sense, but still believe, contra Barnes (2014, 2016a), that it is sometimes wrong simpliciter to cause some disabilities.21 Amalgamating all disability into a 17 See Begon (unpublished) and Sect. 2.1 for a defence of this distinction. 18 In other words, Barnes’s conception of neutrality is very weak (see Wasserman 2018: 254–256; Hawkins 2018: 463–466; Dougherty 2014). 19 For Barnes’s response, see Barnes (2016b). 20 More precisely, since unlike Barnes I distinguish impairment and disability: because they have an impairment widely assumed to be disabling. 21 See Begon (2018b); Wasserman (2018: 255). 946 J. Begon 123 general ‘value-neutral model’, then, can obscure the disadvantage that can be associated with impairment. 22 How problematic this is may depend on the context in which our account of disability is employed. My focus here is relatively narrow: aiming to develop an account that can guide theory and policy that aims to identify and mitigate the disadvantage associated with physical and cognitive difference. Such policies should be nuanced and individualised, as I will argue. They must acknowledge that some impairments, for some people, in some contexts, are not neutral—or merely ‘‘a minority body’’ (Barnes 2016a: 1)—and should not be treated as such. Thus, in this context, at least, it seems unwise to remain committed to a unified category of disability so broadly construed. Like the welfarist account, then, Barnes’s approach shifts the focus of the debate rather than settling it: determining how to respond to disability will require identifying which aspects of which disabilities are bad differences. Neither approach settles the question of when disability is a disadvantage of the kind the state should mitigate. Thus, neither approach can form the basis of public policy or political activism. Whilst we must have a value-neutral account of physical and cognitive difference (which I call impairment), we also need a concept that can play a role in political debates about when difference is disadvantageous, what constitutes injustice towards disabled individuals, and the policies that should be pursued to respond to this. 3 Which inabilities matter? Not all restrictions in individuals’ capacity for activity and participation are disabilities: we are not disabled if we cannot sing, cannot stand on one leg, or cannot raise an eyebrow. This is so even if these abilities are species normal, and even if restrictions in them decrease our welfare. I argue that the relevant restrictions are in abilities that individuals are entitled to be able to perform. I will begin by considering a specific application of this approach: the case of deafness. The impairment here is the inability to hear, whilst the disability is the reduction in relevant opportunities that may arise when most people communicate via speech, such as difficulties in political participation, access to appropriate education, and forming meaningful relationships. Deaf individuals are not disabled on the basis that they are unable to hear music, or the voices of their loved ones. However, this need not be because opportunities for aesthetic experience or forming relationships are 22 As such, Campbell and Stramondo’s (2017: 163–165) suggestion that disabilities are intrinsically neutral, but not instrumentally, comparatively, or overridingly neutral, seems a more plausible and nuanced view. Nonetheless, there may be reasons to worry that their account could also be employed in a way that obscures disadvantages associated with impairments insofar as they tend to consider disabilities ‘‘in isolation from their effects’’ (Campbell and Stramondo’s 2017: 163), where this is usually taken to mean those that are most obviously detrimental to well-being. It is not clear that uncontroversially harmful elements of impairments such as pain, fatigue, or disturbed or depressed emotional states can be meaningfully isolated from these conditions. However, I lack the space to defend this claim here (see Begon (unpublished)). Disability: a justice-based account 947 123 not considered central entitlements. On the contrary, they may well be central—we simply do not need to hear music or voices to have them. Being entitled to opportunities in a domain need not require having every opportunity. Thus, if deaf individuals have access to other aesthetic experiences, their inability to hear music is not a concern of justice. Indeed, if deaf individuals have all the opportunities they are entitled to, they are not disabled. My claim, then, is that individuals are disadvantaged when their access to their entitlements is restricted, and disabled when this results from an impairment (in combination with context, resources, and personal characteristics). 23 Thus, individuals with the same impairments may not be identically disabled, and individuals’ status as disabled may change over time even if their impairment does not alter. Rightly, then, we cannot know whether an individual is disabled merely from information about their impairment. The account is intended to be a framework into which various theories of distributive justice can be incorporated. Accepting the general claim that individuals are disabled when their impairments restrict their access to forms of activity and participation they are entitled to does not require accepting a particular conception of entitlements. However, there is (at least) one approach to distributive justice that cannot be incorporated. My account distinguishes what individuals are entitled to from what merely decreases their welfare. As such, it cannot accommodate those welfarist approaches that consider anything that lowers individuals’ welfare—whether state oppression or stubbing our toe—to constitute a relevant disadvantage. Subjective accounts, which do not distinguish the different reasons for a decrease in hedonic state or the different sorts of preferences individuals may care to have satisfied, would collapse into the welfarist accounts discussed in Sect. 2.3 and so face the same worries about over-inclusiveness and the ubiquity of disability raised there. 24 My approach relies on the general anti-welfarist intuition that ‘‘[s]ome deprivations of capabilities [or resources] express greater disrespect than others, in ways any reasonable person can recognize’’ (Anderson 1999: 332). This distinction is employed widely in the distributive justice literature, by theorists who disagree on 23 This approach may seem similar to Haslangerian models of disability (see Haslanger 2000; Barnes 2016a: 28–38; Howard and Aas 2018), and certainly shares the goals of her ameliorative project. On one plausible iteration of a Haslangerian account, to be disabled is to be in a bodily or psychological state assumed to be an impairment in the prevailing ideology, where this marks one out for pity, stigma and exclusion, and where the fact one is in this state plays a role in one’s systematic disadvantage (Howard and Aas 2018: 1113, 1128–1129). Unlike the account I defend here, this approach is focused not on the specific ‘‘valuable activities’’ individuals are excluded from Howard and Aas (2018: 1113), but with the cause of this exclusion: that it results from possession of a feature that, within the dominant ideology, marks one for this exclusion. As such, this view will be more and less inclusive than my own. Individuals may be disabled though they face very little actual disadvantage [for example, Oscar Pistorius (Howard and Aas 2018: 1129)]. Further, individuals may not be deemed disabled though they face a restriction in opportunities they are entitled to due to atypical bodily or cognitive functioning, if this atypicality is not assumed to be an impairment in the prevailing ideology (for example, the case of obesity discussed in Sect. 7, which though clearly stigmatised is not generally pathologised as an impairment in Howard and Aas’s sense). 24 It is worth noting that it is both implausible that individuals are disabled by anything that lowers their subjective welfare, and implausible that such individuals lack what they are entitled to as a matter of justice, though I cannot defend this stronger claim here. 948 J. Begon 123 much else, and has strong intuitive pull. 25 It is the suggestion that individuals should be entitled to vote in elections, to be mobile, and to access educational opportunities, but are not entitled to access every ride in an amusement park, or a sports car, or an expensive musical instrument—and that this is so even if they would prefer these latter opportunities, and they would have a greater positive impact on their welfare. In other words, this is the claim that only some domains of life are the concern of justice, and that the scope of these domains is not determined by individuals’ preferences. Beyond this restriction, then, adopting a specific theory of justice is not a prerequisite to accepting my account of disability. However, it is difficult to defend this account in the abstract, and cumbersome to run through every possible way to cash out individual entitlements. Thus, I will talk in specific terms, employing an approach with three key features. First, I will assume individuals are entitled to capabilities, understood as control over certain domains of their life, rather than merely access to resources (Begon 2017). Second, our conception of entitlements should be relatively thick: not merely entailing the fulfilment of basic needs, but including access to opportunities such as forming social relationships, engaging in leisure activities, and enjoying aesthetic experiences. Finally, I assume that individuals are entitled to broadly specified opportunities, and not particular or identical functionings: for example, opportunities for aesthetic experiences, mobility, or communication, and not hearing music, walking, or talking. 26 These features have not been selected at random. I believe there are good reasons to opt for an account of distributive justice with these features, and that reflection on disability can help demonstrate why this is so, as much of the subsequent discussion will illustrate. However, I certainly cannot definitively refute all alternative understand- ings of entitlements here, so will leave it to their adherents to demonstrate how they can navigate the issues disability raises. 4 Feasibility, levelling-down, and thinning-out I will now outline some possible objections to the account I have sketched, and in responding to them in subsequent sections will elucidate my account. First, it may be objected that if being disabled means lacking opportunities we are entitled to, then impairments that result in the loss of significant opportunities will not be considered disabling if we cannot prevent this loss, since we cannot be entitled to an opportunity it is impossible to provide. Thus, if, due to lack of medical or technological knowledge, or merely lack of resources, we cannot prevent 25 For example, Anderson (1999), Dworkin (2000: 61), Carter (2014: 84–85). I will not defend this distinction here (see Begon 2016). 26 Approaches that accept some version of the second criterion but not the third—i.e. an expansive, but narrowly specified set of entitlements—are common (arguably including: Dworkin 2000; Nussbaum 2000; Cohen 2011; Rawls 1999; Anderson 1999). I have defended the third criteria elsewhere (Begon 2017). Also see Asch and Wasserman (2005) for an argument that individuals need not have access to every opportunity. Disability: a justice-based account 949 123 individuals being rendered immobile, unable to communicate, or to form relationships, then they cannot be entitled to these opportunities, and cannot be considered disabled by their absence. If this were so, serious impairments—perhaps the most serious impairments—would not be considered disabling on my account. Clearly, this would be very counterintuitive. Further, this understanding of our entitlements presents a dilemma. On the one hand, this may lead us to conclude that individuals with serious impairments should simply have different entitlements. That is, if some individuals can only be provided with a restricted set of opportunities, then their entitlements are correspondingly diminished. On the other hand, we may wish to resist this tiered, non-universal approach to entitlements, and insist instead that all humans are entitled to the same opportunities (though not, of course, to the same outcomes). Yet this seems to imply that the content of everyone’s entitlements should reflect the unavoidable constraints on some individuals’ functioning. In other words, that we can be entitled only to what can be provided to all. If we grasp this latter horn, the content of our entitlements might start to look rather thin. This is implausible in itself and will generate an implausible account of disability if my approach is employed. For example, if we cannot currently enable everyone to control their mobility then no one can be entitled to this opportunity, and individuals whose control over their mobility is impaired are not disabled by their inability. However, this is an artificial dichotomy. If we reject an implausibly strict egalitarian view, according to which everyone must be enabled to perform an identical set of functionings, and instead consider individuals to be entitled to generalised opportunities—for example, mobility, not walking (i.e. the third criterion outlined above)—then it may seem that everyone can have the same entitlements. Thus, we can avoid a tiered approach without levelling-down our entitlements to include only those capabilities to function that can be universally provided. That is, we should recognise that capabilities are multiply-realisable, and treat different functionings as interchangeable and equally valuable. This will mean that many individuals with impairments can have the opportunities they are entitled to even if there are some functionings they cannot perform. Thus, even if we were to limit our entitlements to those that could be provided universally, this might eliminate less than it initially seems. Nonetheless, this response will not prove fully satisfactory. First, even if the opportunities individuals are entitled to are generalised and multiply-realisable there will still be some cases in which they cannot be provided. Staying with the example of mobility: though individuals with many mobility impairments can be enabled to control their mobility, this may not be possible for individuals with locked-in syndrome. Further, the very focus on multiply-realisable capabilities may generate a further objection about the ‘thinning-out’ of individuals’ entitlements. It might seem that if those who use a wheelchair have sufficient opportunity to be mobile, then they have all they are entitled to. Thus, if, for example, it were possible to restore functioning to a paraplegic person’s legs, even at very little cost, they would neither be entitled to demand this from the state nor considered disabled if the treatment were not provided. This is an instance of the more general worry that sufficientarian approaches, by only ensuring individuals reach some threshold of achievement, may 950 J. Begon 123 fail to eliminate radical, and potentially unjust, inequalities above this threshold. If capabilities can be experienced in various ways, then individuals are neither considered disabled by their inability to perform specific functionings (walking, talking, hearing, seeing) nor entitled to be enabled to perform them, just as long as they have more general capabilities (for mobility, communication, leisure, aesthetic experiences) at some appropriate level. I will now respond to these objections. 5 Identifying distributive entitlements I turn, first, to the objection that individuals with serious impairments will not be considered disabled if the opportunity loss associated with their condition cannot be avoided; and, further, that we will therefore face the dilemma of either decreasing entitlements for this subset of individuals or levelling-down entitlements generally. This is based on the assumption that the demands of distributive justice must be realisable: that if an individual is entitled to something, it must be feasible to provide it to them. However, we need not accept this assumption. 27 It is quite plausible to suggest that we are currently unable to rectify some instances of injustice. Thus, some individuals may not be able to access opportunities that justice requires they have. If a just state of affairs is not currently realisable then they cannot have a claim that anyone now provides these opportunities, though they do have a claim that we work towards a situation in which their provision is feasible. If, for example, we believe all humans are entitled to control over their mobility, then this cannot mean the state has an obligation to provide this to someone with locked- in syndrome if this is impossible. However, they do have an obligation to enable them to have such control if it were, and to work towards releasing this state of affairs. Further, the individual with locked-in syndrome is disabled because they cannot be provided with an opportunity that they should have access to: that they should be enabled to perform if this were possible. A situation in which some individuals lack opportunities that everyone should be entitled to may be unjust, then, even if no one is guilty of causing this injustice and no one has a direct duty to rectify it. Some may find the suggestion that entitlements should be conditional in this sense implausible: how can we be entitled to something no one has a duty to provide? It is worth noting, first, that the alternative approach has similarly unappealing implications: if we want a universal list of entitlements and can only include items on this list when they can currently be provided to every individual, then we may not even have a general right to nourishment, say, if it is currently logistically impossible to ensure everyone has this opportunity. We may, therefore, accept that some entitlements should lack a feasibility constraint, but believe these conditional or proto-entitlements should be distinguished from entitlements proper, where the former are what all individuals are (conditionally) owed as a matter of justice and the latter are those claims that we can press against a 27 I cannot attempt to conclusively refute the feasibility constraint on justice here, but for an excellent argument for its rejection, see Gheaus (2013). Disability: a justice-based account 951 123 specific duty-bearer. The former constitute part of the content of a theory of distributive justice: the list of capabilities (or primary goods or human rights) to which all individuals have a (conditional) entitlement, even if they temporarily cannot be provided with every item on this list. Indeed, this captures what seems so objectionable about situations in which individuals do not have the opportunities (or resources, or rights) we think they ought to: individuals may not be wronged when they cannot be mobile, or nourished, and so on, but they should have these opportunities if it were possible and we should work to make this so. The important point is not the choice of terminology, but the general claim that the set of entitlements specified by a theory of distributive justice are, in a sense, owed to all, even when this obligation cannot feasibly be met. The sense in which they are owed is that these opportunities (resources, rights) should be provided if they can be, and that the state (or other relevant body) should not artificially limit the boundaries of the possible. This means that not all disability will be the result of unjust behaviour—though, of course, some will be. Sometimes the state may fail to fund research to develop technologies that increase impaired individuals’ function- ing capacity, or design material infrastructure in avoidably exclusionary ways. Yet sometimes the restrictions to individuals’ entitlements may be ineliminable and unavoidable: perhaps due to natural obstacles, perhaps due to competing claims on a limited pool of resources, or to conflicts between different forms of accommodation (certain policies may render some impairments non-disabling (indeed, may be the only way to do so) whilst at the same time exacerbating others). Thus, the content of our (conditional) universal distributive entitlements should not be determined by what it is feasible to provide universally. Understanding entitlements in this way means we need not grasp either horn of the above dilemma: we can have a universal set of entitlements that is not levelled- down to include only those opportunities that can be achieved by all. However, this does not imply that the content of our entitlements can or should take no account of feasibility whatsoever. We could, for example, take the view that humans should be entitled to the opportunities necessary for a decent life, where this will be informed by our reasonable expectations of what such a life entails. On this view, controlling our mobility might be central to such a life; the ability to fly would not be. Further, the content of our reasonable expectations for a decent life can be predicted to change over time, as technology improves. The point, here, is not to identify the specific content of our distributive entitlements, nor even to outline the method by which they would be determined. Rather, it is to note that this might depend on what it is possible for humans to do, and on what we think humans ought to be able to do, without implying that all these entitlements must currently be achievable for every human. In other words, entitlements can be indexed to what is feasible for most, without requiring that they can be provided to all (though we should strive to achieve this). Two further objections may be raised against this response. First, if our entitlements depend to some extent on our reasonable expectations about a decent (or dignified, or flourishing) human life, and our expectations are informed by what humans, as a species, can generally do, then this might seem to collapse into a species norm approach. That is, our entitlements are simply identical to species- 952 J. Begon 123 normal functionings. Yet this is not the case. Even without specifying the content of our entitlements we can see that they will be both narrower and broader than species-normal functionings. They will be narrower, first, because on any plausible view trivial human capabilities will not be central entitlements (the ability to roll our tongue, sing, or stand on one leg). Individuals who thus deviate from the species norm do not lack opportunities they are entitled to. Our entitlements are narrower, too, if understood as general opportunities, rather than the performance of specific functionings. An individual can have what they are entitled to (the capability for mobility, say), even if there is a species-normal functioning they cannot perform (walking using their own legs). Additionally, our entitlements will be broader, since we may be entitled to more opportunities than those that are ‘natural’ or normal for our species. 28 As medical, social, and technological progress expands the scope of human capacities, our reasonable expectations of a decent life and the opportunities we should be entitled to will surely reflect this. A second objection concerns the potential ambiguity regarding when it is ‘feasible’ to provide an opportunity, given that this may require radical expense of time or resources. There are two forms of this worry. First, if we could all be enabled to fly, say—if the government were to divert all research funding to this project—then should this opportunity be an entitlement, which we are disabled in the absence of? Clearly the answer is no. When this is a mere abstract possibility, such a functioning is unlikely to feature in our reasonable conception of a decent life, or what we can reasonably expect from the state. However, I would concede that if a way of enabling humans to fly were discovered and made available to the majority, then we might expand our conception of our entitlements to include this. 29 In this imagined scenario this is no more a reduction ad absurdum of my approach than acknowledging that individuals’ capacity for mobility should take account of modern transportation and that, as such, someone who could only get around at the speed and distance walking and running would usually allow may not have what they are entitled to in this domain. To emphasise: insisting that we can be entitled to opportunities it is infeasible to provide universally does not mean our entitlements must be entirely unmoored from what is feasible for most. Second, and perhaps more troubling, are cases in which an opportunity is available to most individuals, but can only be provided to a minority at great expense. For example, if an individual with locked-in syndrome can control their mobility only with an extremely expensive piece of equipment, are they entitled to it? No doubt there will be many difficult cases, but our approach to such questions must involve weighing up the capabilities provided to the minority against those lost by the majority. Thus, if the cost of providing this equipment meant others suffered premature death or significant impairment then the individual surely cannot be entitled to their mobility in the face of these costs. In this case, we can continue to 28 The species norm approach will be restricted to ‘natural’ human abilities if we follow Daniels (1985: 28) and derive it from the ‘‘design of the organism’’, rather than ‘‘merely a statistical notion’’. 29 Thanks to Paul Billingham for pushing me to clarify this point. Disability: a justice-based account 953 123 say that it is impossible for the individual to be mobile and they are unavoidably disabled, since their entitlements cannot be provided at a reasonable cost. 30 6 Beyond minimal functionings I now turn to the worry that understanding entitlements as general, multiply- realisable opportunities will mean that individuals will not be considered disabled even when they lack important opportunities. First, I consider Anita Silvers’s objection to what she takes to be capability theorists’ approach to educational provision for individuals with impairments. This, she claims, would only provide ‘‘educational opportunity adequate for a dignified life, which…may not even…rise to the level of average educational attainment’’ (Silvers 2009: 181). Silvers discusses a child with a hearing impairment, who struggles to catch all the information imparted in class due to the difficulty of lip-reading in this context. Nonetheless, she is denied a translator since her educational attainment is already above average (Silvers 2009: 177–182). Silvers objects that it is unfair that children with impairments are unable to fulfil their potential simply because their educational environment is not designed to support them. Further, it might seem that, on my view, these children would (implausibly) not be considered disabled by this restriction in their access to education, because ‘they already have what they’re entitled to’. However, contra Silvers, a decent education surely requires more than the opportunity for some minimal educative outcome, such as passing grades. 31 More plausibly, this requires something like ‘the opportunity to develop our potential to a similar degree as our peers’. This must be at least part of the goal of education, and we would fail to show individuals equal concern and respect if we provided this to some and not others. 32 This does not mean that there will not be difficult cases, where the needs and requirements of different children pull in different directions, and limitations of resources mean that an ideal learning environment cannot be provided for everyone. However, as discussed, the fact that something cannot 30 This does not imply scarcity is wholly irrelevant to our entitlements. Again, my claim is only that the possibility of universal provision is not a prerequisite to something being an entitlement. Feasibility, including considerations of scarcity, may play a role in determining where the boundaries of our entitlements lie: for example, as discussed, via informing our reasonable expectations about the shape of a decent life. Returning to the above example, if individual jet-pack technology were created but was prohibitively expensive and/or relied on a resource too scarce for it to be made available to all, then this is not likely to feature amongst our reasonable expectations and thus our entitlements. In contrast, if this could be provided near-universally, became the dominant mode of transport and a prerequisite for participation in various aspects of social and political life, then this may be amongst our (conditional) entitlements. 31 The same is true if we focus on other criteria to identify entitlements, such as leading a dignified or flourishing life. Indeed, if a criterion did not have this implication, this would surely count as a reason against its adoption. 32 See Terzi (2008) for a capability approach to education for children with impairments. 954 J. Begon 123 currently be universally provided does not mean that we cannot reasonably include this amongst our entitlements. Yet it may be objected that education is a special case. Whilst the very goal of education involves enabling individuals to develop their talents and abilities, having opportunities for mobility, communication, or leisure surely does not require being able to fulfil our potential in these domains. It seems much more plausible to suggest that we are here entitled to something like acceptable options and the capacity to meaningfully choose between them. As such, individuals who achieve mobility with a wheelchair rather than by walking, or communicate using Sign rather than speech, or look at art because they are unable to listen to music, are not considered disabled by this restriction in their ability to function; nor would they be entitled to an operation to restore the use of their legs, or cochlear implants to restore their hearing, even if this would not be costly. In these cases, I would bite the bullet—though with some important caveats. I would accept, then, that if we lived in circumstances in which individuals with impairments had all the opportunities they are entitled to then they should neither be considered disabled nor necessarily entitled to state assistance. For example, if an individual with a mobility impairment could control their mobility without being dependent on others, then they may not be entitled to be enabled to walk. 33 Similarly, a deaf individual who had access to leisure activities and aesthetic experiences (and every other capability they are entitled to) would not be entitled to cochlear implants to allow them to hear music. Nor would these individuals be considered disabled. The caveats, though, are to point out, first, that often individuals with impairments do not have what they are entitled to. In many cases the restrictions in their capabilities are avoidable, and could be eliminated by changing social infrastructure and norms. However, this is not always so. In some instances, this is because we lack the technology or resources to prevent some impairments from restricting individuals’ opportunities. In others, this is because individuals’ needs conflict, and there is no way to structure the external environment that would eliminate all restrictions. For example, ‘‘[p]eople with mobility issues who do not use wheelchairs may find that steps are safer and easier for them than ramps…[w]heelchair users may have problems with tactile paving which gives locational cues to visually impaired people’’, and so on (Shakespeare 2006: 46). These cases can prove as intractable as those in which we simply lack the ability to institute the relevant change. As such, the appropriate way to mitigate the disadvantage associated with an impairment may not be to change the environment, and this might be so even when the disadvantage is a result of that environment. Thus, to conclude that if an impairment were not disabling (did not result in relevant restrictions) an individual would not be entitled to state assistance does not imply that now, or in the near future, treatments that mitigate impairments would not be provided. 33 Exactly how much of their environment would have to be inaccessible to conclude that an individual lacks control over their mobility is ambiguous, and I will not attempt to settle this question here. Disability: a justice-based account 955 123 The second caveat is to note that suggesting that such treatments may not be a matter of entitlement does not imply that they are banned or restricted. Any liberal approach to distributive justice will aim to ensure both fairness in distribution, and individuals’ freedom to form and pursue their own conception of the good. Thus, if an individual desires to walk, or hear, or see, they will not be prevented from pursuing these goals. Indeed, in a situation in which individuals had access to all the central capabilities (or primary goods, or equality of Dworkinian resources) there would be sufficient resource equality that individuals would have the ability to achieve these goals (especially on the above assumption that these treatments are inexpensive). Indeed, my account does not even rule out state provision or subsidy of these options on the grounds of public choice, if the decision is procedurally just and does not divert resources from the satisfaction of actual entitlements. 34 One final sense in which our entitlements might seem too minimal on my approach relates to an objection earlier raised against the species norm approach. This is, that by focussing on what individuals are able to do, I take insufficient account of how much more difficult this may be when we have an impairment. Someone who uses a wheelchair, for example, may have the capability for mobility, but this will often be restricted by both the built and natural environment. Thus, they may find travelling much more physically demanding than, for example, walking a similar distance. Or, an individual in chronic pain may be able to perform all the functionings that a person without this condition can, yet they must struggle against the pain that accompanies every functioning they perform. I certainly want to resist the implication that the difficulty of performing tasks would not be considered a relevant dimension of disadvantage, and that individuals who experience such difficulty would not be considered disabled, nor entitled to assistance to mitigate it. Whether this is indeed an implication of my approach depends on the sensitivity of our conception of distributive entitlements not just to what we can do, but also to the pain and effort that must be expended to do it. I would contend that such concerns should feature in our understanding of individuals’ entitlements. 35 Although I cannot provide an independent defence of this here, it is important to note that insisting that a theory of distributive justice is sensitive to these considerations is not merely a post hoc modification to ensure that my definition of disability remains plausible. On the contrary, the above examples give us reason to think that individuals should be entitled not just to the mere capacity to perform some functionings, but to be able to do so without associated pain, and without having to expend massively more energy than others to achieve the same outcome. Thus, the point is not that an account of our entitlements that ignored the pain and effort required to achieve them would generate an implausible account of disability if my framework is employed, but that this would be an independently implausible account of our entitlements. 34 Thanks to Carl Fox for helping me clarify this point. 35 For approaches that do so, see Wolff and de-Shalit (2007), Wolff (2009a, b), Cohen (2011), Anderson (1999). It may be a problem with Nussbaum’s (2000, 2006) and Sen’s (1999, 2009) approaches that they do not clearly incorporate such concerns. 956 J. Begon 123 7 What counts, who’s disabled? I will finish by considering whether my account will prove to be too revisionary. Certainly, the impairments that would be considered disabling do not neatly cohere with our intuitions in a number of cases. As emphasised from the outset, my account will imply that individuals with visible impairments may not be disabled by them, that individuals with seemingly minor or invisible impairments may be disabled, and that individuals’ status as disabled may change across time and context. However, far from giving us reason to reject this approach, this is one of its key benefits. As Sect. 2.4 discussed, there is little point in devising a definition that captures all paradigm case when we have good reason to think the paradigm is informed by prejudice and misinformation. First, many paradigm impairments, such as deafness, blindness, paraplegia, achondroplasia (a common form of dwarfism), ASCs, and Down’s syndrome need not be disabling on my account. If individuals have the opportunities they are entitled to—perhaps as a result of adequate infrastructure, access to resources, and lack of bias—they will not be considered disabled merely on the basis of their impairment. Disability does not consist in bodily or cognitive difference, but in specific opportunity losses that might result. This does not imply that we cannot campaign for the better treatment of individuals with impairments, or for their access to their entitlements. However, we should not assume that having an impairment, especially a visible impairment, must be disadvantageous. We should, instead, focus on the specifics of each case and determine whether an impairment is actually associated with restrictions in individuals’ activity and participation. The reality often will not accord with our unexamined intuitions. 36 My approach will also produce deviations from the paradigm in the other direction: many non-paradigm cases, such as depression and anxiety, and even obesity or shyness, might be disabling. Further, individuals who have body integrity identity disorder (the strong desire to amputate a healthy limb) may be disabled by being prevented from undergoing this amputation, insofar as living with a limb they disassociate from disrupts their access to capabilities: for example, making social interaction difficult. 37 I will consider perhaps the most controversial of these examples: obesity. I am aware that both disabled and obese individuals will likely object to this implication, given the unjustified stigma attached to both labels. It is worth emphasising, then, that though I consider an obese body an impairment (after all, it is a deviation from the species norm), I am not suggesting that it worse, or 36 As noted in Sect. 2.1, part of the motive behind the introduction of the social model, and the rhetoric of claiming that ‘‘disablement is nothing to do with the body’’ (Oliver 1996: 35), was to resist the medicalisation of disability and to highlight the contingency of the connection between impairment and disadvantage. 37 For discussion of these cases, see Bayne and Levy (2005), Müller (2009). Disability: a justice-based account 957 123 necessarily disadvantageous, to have such a body. However, this is a dimension of difference, like many others, that may be associated with disadvantage. 38 My focus is not the possible (and sometimes controversial) correlation between obesity and health conditions such as high blood pressure, diabetes, heart attack, or stroke. Even leaving these aside merely having an obese body can be disabling. Our built environment is made for human bodies of a particular size and weight. As Gay (2017: 184) says, ‘‘[t]here are very few spaces where bodies like mine fit’’. One simple and important example is chairs: aeroplane seats, restaurant booths, lecture theatres, cinema seats. If these cannot accommodate individuals with larger bodies, this can be hugely restrictive to those who possess them, limiting opportunities to be mobile, to access education, or to engage in many leisure activities. In addition, an obese body may be restrictive independently of the design of material infrastructure, rendering ‘‘impossible’’ activities like standing for long periods or walking a mile uphill (Gay 2017: 16). Finally, the bias, stigma, and abuse obese individuals are often subject to, the commentaries on their bodies by friends, family, medical professionals, and strangers, and the assumptions made about their capacities may further limit their capabilities. Options may be closed to them because others assume they are incapable of exercising them (for example, not being offered certain jobs), or they may lack internal capabilities (for example, not feeling qualified to apply for these jobs in the first place). 39 In all these ways, obesity—like other forms of physical and cognitive difference—can be disabling. The final counterintuitive implication is that what counts as a disability on my view will be contextualised, and may change over time. This can happen in at least three ways. First, as society becomes better able to accommodate impairments, and enable different forms of functioning, then these impairments will cease to be disabling. This is not because these impairments are ‘cured’, but because their link with disadvantage is severed. For example, if the oft-discussed examples of deafness and mobility impairments no longer lead to capability loss, then individuals with these impairments may not be disabled, though they still cannot hear or walk unaided. Whilst this may seem counterintuitive to some, it accords with the experience of many disabled individuals, who do not regret, or demand compensation for, the different ways they function. Consider, for example, Harriet McBryde Johnson’s (2003) account of the pleasures of wheelchair use, and the misperceptions of those who do not use one: I used to try to explain the fact that I enjoy my life, that it’s a great sensual pleasure to zoom by power chair on these delicious muggy streets, that I have no more reason to kill myself than most people. But it gets tedious…they don’t want to know. They think they know everything there is to know just by 38 There are, of course, some differences correlated with disadvantage that we would not want to describe as disabilities, such as our gender or racial identity, or sexual orientation. As Sect. 2.1 considered, this need not be an implication of my view. 39 In Nussbaum’s (2000: 84) terminology, internal capabilities are ‘‘developed states of the person herself that are…sufficient conditions for the exercise of requisite functions’’. Whether restrictions in internal capabilities constitute a loss of entitlements depend on the conception of entitlements we employ. Again, such examples may give us reason to incorporate them. 958 J. Begon 123 looking at me. That’s how stereotypes work. They don’t know that they’re confused. Second, as our capacity to provide opportunities changes, individuals may be entitled to more if the content of our entitlements depends on our reasonable expectations. For example, we now expect leisure time, aesthetic experiences, and a longer life than previously. Impairments that restrict access to these new entitlements will then count as disabling, though individuals’ actual abilities have not changed. One example here might be (some forms of) dyslexia. In a context in which many are illiterate, this is unlikely to be disabling. In a context in which a grasp of the written word is a prerequisite for many other opportunities, it would be. Thus, dyslexic individuals may become disabled over time, or by moving. Consider, for example, a dyslexic girl who emigrates from rural Gambia, where illiteracy is rife and educational infrastructure underdeveloped, to the UK, where she has better access to education, though her dyslexia is not fully accommodated. Whilst she is now less disadvantaged (she now has access to education), she may also become disabled insofar as it is now her impairment that restricts her access to education (where previously it may have been poverty or sexism). Again, this seems to be the right way to understand such cases. Lastly, individuals who have impairments that involve periodic and perhaps unpredictable flare-ups, such as fatigue and pain conditions, may have a changeable disability status. Some will be disabled only during a flare-up, some may be disabled during periods when flare-ups are common, and for some the mere possibility of a flare-up may render them consistently disabled. For example, an individual with epilepsy may never be able to drive a car, or an individual with ME may struggle to retain employment if their impairment necessitates frequent absences. 8 Conclusion It is a consequence of my approach that individuals are not categorised as disabled in the way we might expect, and that who is included in this category may change. Yet surely it is right to set aside our preconceptions about how bad some impairment must be and focus instead on the actual restrictions individuals face, and on which of these should be the focus of our concern. What matters—what is disabling—is that individuals are rendered (often contingently) unable to be mobile, unable to communicate or form social relationships, or unable to access education or meaningful work as a result of their impairments. Not that they are unable to walk, unable to listen to music, or unable to read emotional cues easily. Whatever account of distributive justice is used, then, my approach to disability will be revisionary and contrary to many common-sense intuitions about who is disabled. However, these implications constitute a feature, not a bug. Our present intuitions concerning what constitutes disability often reflect prejudice and bias, and should be altered. Further, our account of disability should change over time, and reflect what individuals are able to do, and what we think they ought to be able to do. The problem of disability is the problem of losing significant opportunities—and not the ‘problem’ of Disability: a justice-based account 959 123 deviation from the species norm, or the loss of our irrelevant opportunities—and our understanding of disability should be reoriented to reflect this. Acknowledgements For helpful comments and discussion of earlier drafts, I would like to thank Alice Baderin, Ian Carroll, Cécile Fabre, Carl Fox, Katherine Jenkins, and audiences at the Royal Institute of Philosophy Seminar at the University of Nottingham, the Nuffield Political Theory Workshop, the Pri- ority in Practice Conference at the University of Oxford, the Association of Social and Political Philosophy Conference at the University of Sheffield, and the Political Philosophy Seminar at the University of Newcastle, as well as an anonymous referee. Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article’s Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article’s Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http:// creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/. References Aas, S. (2016). Disabled—therefore, unhealthy? Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 9, 1259–1274. American Psychiatric Association: Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders, Fifth Edition (DSM-5). (2013). Arlington, VA.: American Psychiatric Association. Anderson, E. (1999). What is the point of equality? Ethics, 109, 287–337. Asch, A., & Wasserman, D. (2005). Where is the sin in synecdoche? In D. Wasserman, J. Bickenbach, & R. Wachbroit (Eds.), Quality of life and human difference: Genetic testing, health care (pp. 172–216). New York: Cambridge University Press. Barclay, L. (2010). Disability, respect and justice. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 27, 154–171. Barnes, E. (2009). Disability and adaptive preference. Philosophical Perspectives, 23, 1–22. Barnes, E. (2014). Valuing disability, causing disability. Ethics, 125, 88–113. Barnes, E. (2016a). The minority body: A theory of disability. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Barnes, E. (2016b). Reply to Kahane and Savulescu. Research Philosophica, 93, 295–309. Barnes, E. (2018). Against impairment: Replies to Aas, Howard, and Francis. Philosophical Studies, 175, 1151–1162. Bayne, T., & Levy, N. (2005). Amputees by choice: Body integrity identity disorder and the ethics of amputation. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 22, 75–86. Begon, J. (2016). Athletic policy, passive well-being: defending freedom in the capability approach. Economics and Philosophy, 32, 51–73. Begon, J. (2017). Capabilities for all? From capabilities to function, to capabilities to control. Social Theory and Practice, 43, 154–179. Begon, J. (2018a). Disability, rationality, and justice: Disambiguating adaptive preferences. In D. Wasserman & A. Cureton (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy and disability. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Begon, J. (2018b). Book review: Elizabeth Barnes, the minority body: A Theory of disability. Journal of Moral Philosophy, 15, 100–103. Begon, J. (unpublished). Neutral impairment, disadvantageous disability. Bettcher, T. M. (2014a). Feminist perspectives on trans issues. In E. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopaedia of philosophy. Retrieved May 16, 2020 from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/ spr2014/entries/feminism-trans/. Bettcher, T. M. (2014b). Trapped in the wrong theory: Rethinking trans oppression and resistance. Signs, 39, 383–406. 960 J. Begon 123 http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/feminism-trans/ https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/feminism-trans/ Buchanan, A., Brock, D. W., Daniels, N., & Wikler, D. (2000). From chance to choice: Genetics and justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Campbell, S. M., & Stramondo, J. A. (2016). Review: The minority body by Elizabeth Barnes. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. Retrieved May 16, 2020 from https://ndpr.nd.edu/news/the-minority- body-a-theory-of-disability/. Campbell, S. M., & Stramondo, J. A. (2017). The complicated relationship of disability and well-being. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 27, 151–184. Carter, I. (2014). Is the capability approach paternalist? Economics and Philosophy, 30, 75–98. Cohen, G. A. (2011). On the currency of egalitarian justice. In M. Otsuka (Ed.), On the currency of egalitarian justice and other essays in political philosophy (pp. 3–43). Princeton: Princeton University Press. Crisp, R. (2006). Reasons and the good. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Daniels, N. (1985). Just health care. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Daniels, N., Rose, S., & Daniels Zide, E. (2009). Disability, adaptation, and inclusion. In K. Brownlee & A. Cureton (Eds.), Disability and disadvantage (pp. 54–85). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Dembroff, R. (forthcoming). Real talk on the metaphysics of gender. Philosophical Topics. Dougherty, T. (2014). Ethics discussion at PEA Soup: Elizabeth Barnes’ ‘‘Valuing Disability, Causing Disability’’. PEA Soup. Available at: https://peasoup.typepad.com/peasoup/2014/11/ethics- discussion-at-pea-soup-elizabeth-barnes-valuing-disability-causing-disability-with-critical-p.html. Dworkin, R. (2000). Sovereign virtue. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Elster, J. (1987). Sour grapes: Studies in the subversion of rationality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Francis, L. (2018). Understanding disability civil rights non-categorically: The minority body and the Americans with disabilities act. Philosophical Studies, 175, 1135–1149. Gay, R. (2017). Hunger: A memoir of (my) body. London: Corsair. Gheaus, A. (2013). The feasibility constraint on the concept of justice. The Philosophical Quarterly, 63, 445–464. Griffin, J. (1986). Well-being: Its meaning, measurement, and moral importance. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Haslanger, S. (2000). Gender and race: (What) Are they? (what) do we want them to be? Nous, 34, 31–55. Hawkins, J. (2018). Book review: Elizabeth Barnes, the minority body: A theory of disability. Ethics, 128, 462–467. Howard, D., & Aas, S. (2018). On valuing impairment. Philosophical Studies, 175, 1113–1133. Jenkins, K. (2016). Amelioration and inclusion: Gender identity and the concept of woman. Ethics, 126, 394–421. Kahane, G., & Savulescu, J. (2009). The welfarist account of disability. In K. Brownlee & A. Cureton (Eds.), Disability and disadvantage (pp. 14–53). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Kahane, G., & Savulescu, J. (2016). Disability and mere difference. Ethics, 126, 774–788. Kahneman, D., Slovic, P., & Tversky, A. (Eds.). (1982). Judgement under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Khader, S. (2011). Adaptive preferences and women’s empowerment. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Kittay, E. F. (2011). Forever small: The strange case of ashley X. Hypatia, 26, 610–631. McBryde Johnson, H. (2003). Unspeakable conversations. The New York times magazine. http://www. nytimes.com/2003/02/16/magazine/unspeakable-conversations.html. Retrieved from 24 June 2019. Müller, S. (2009). Body integrity identity disorder (BIID)—Is the amputation of healthy limbs ethically justified? The American Journal of Bioethics, 9, 36–43. Nussbaum, M. C. (2000). Women and human development. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Nussbaum, M. C. (2006). Frontiers of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Oliver, M. (1996). Understanding disability: From theory to practice. Basingstoke: Palgrave. Parfit, D. (1984). Reasons and persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Rawls, J. (1999). A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Savulescu, J., & Kahane, G. (2009). The moral obligation to create children with the best chance of the best life. Bioethics, 23, 274–290. Scanlon, T. M. (1975). Preference and urgency. The Journal of Philosophy, 72, 655–669. Scanlon, T. M. (1998). What we owe to each other. Harvard: Belknap Press. Sen, A. (1999). Development as freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Sen, A. (2009). The idea of justice. London: Penguin. Shakespeare, T. (2006). Disability rights and wrongs: Revisited. New York: Routledge. Disability: a justice-based account 961 123 https://ndpr.nd.edu/news/the-minority-body-a-theory-of-disability/ https://ndpr.nd.edu/news/the-minority-body-a-theory-of-disability/ https://peasoup.typepad.com/peasoup/2014/11/ethics-discussion-at-pea-soup-elizabeth-barnes-valuing-disability-causing-disability-with-critical-p.html https://peasoup.typepad.com/peasoup/2014/11/ethics-discussion-at-pea-soup-elizabeth-barnes-valuing-disability-causing-disability-with-critical-p.html http://www.nytimes.com/2003/02/16/magazine/unspeakable-conversations.html http://www.nytimes.com/2003/02/16/magazine/unspeakable-conversations.html Silvers, A. (2009). No talent? Beyond the worst off! a diverse theory of justice for disability. In K. Brownlee & A. Cureton (Eds.), Disability and disadvantage (pp. 163–199). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Smith, S. R. (2001). The social construction of talent: A defence of justice as reciprocity. Journal of Political Philosophy, 9, 19–37. Sumner, W. (1996). Welfare, happiness, and ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Terzi, L. (2004). ‘The social model of disability: A philosophical critique. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 2, 141–157. Terzi, L. (2008). Justice and equality in education: A capability perspective on disability and special educational needs. London: Continuum. Terzi, L. (2009). Vagaries of the natural lottery? Human diversity, disability, and justice: A capability perspective. In K. Brownlee & A. Cureton (Eds.), Disability and disadvantage (pp. 86–111). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Wahlert, L., & Gill, S. (2017). Pathological, disabled, transgender: The ethics, history, laws, and contradictions in models that best serve transgender rights. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 27, 249–266. Wasserman, D. (2018). Book review: The minority body: A theory of disability, Elizabeth Barnes. The Philosophical Review, 127, 251–256. WHO. (2017). Health topics: Disability. Geneva: World Health Organisation. Retrieved from 24 June 2019. Wolff, J. (2009a). Disability among equals. In K. Brownlee & A. Cureton (Eds.), Disability and disadvantage (pp. 112–137). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Wolff, J. (2009b). Disability, status enhancement, personal enhancement, and resource allocation. Economics and Philosophy, 25, 49–68. Wolff, J., & de-Shalit, A. (2007). Disadvantage. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Publisher’s Note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. 962 J. Begon 123 Disability: a justice-based account Abstract The problem of defining disability What disability is not Disability and impairment Species norm accounts Welfarist accounts Barnes’s social constructionist approach Which inabilities matter? Feasibility, levelling-down, and thinning-out Identifying distributive entitlements Beyond minimal functionings What counts, who’s disabled? Conclusion Acknowledgements References work_5mfznh7q4rhzdaebmvvq3pqawi ---- PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE This article was downloaded by: [Gorski, Paul] On: 10 July 2009 Access details: Access Details: [subscription number 913075635] Publisher Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK Intercultural Education Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/title~content=t713393965 Intercultural education as social justice Paul C. Gorski a a George Mason University, USA Online Publication Date: 01 April 2009 To cite this Article Gorski, Paul C.(2009)'Intercultural education as social justice',Intercultural Education,20:2,87 — 90 To link to this Article: DOI: 10.1080/14675980902922135 URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/14675980902922135 Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.informaworld.com/terms-and-conditions-of-access.pdf This article may be used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, re-distribution, re-selling, loan or sub-licensing, systematic supply or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae and drug doses should be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims, proceedings, demand or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material. http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/title~content=t713393965 http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/14675980902922135 http://www.informaworld.com/terms-and-conditions-of-access.pdf Intercultural Education Vol. 20, No. 2, April 2009, 87–90 ISSN 1467-5986 print/ISSN 1469-8439 online © 2009 Taylor & Francis DOI: 10.1080/14675980902922135 http://www.informaworld.com EDITORIAL Intercultural education as social justice Taylor and FrancisCEJI_A_392385.sgm10.1080/14675980902922135Intercultural Education1467-5986 (print)/1469-8439 (online)Original Article2009Taylor & Francis202000000April 2009Assistant Professor Paul C.Gorskigorski@EdChange.org John sat nervously, tapping a pencil on his desk. As Blue River High School’s dean of students, he had asked me to help ‘mediate’ the growing tension between the school’s administrators and an increasingly organized group of lesbian, gay, bisexual, and transgender (LGBT) students. Located in the southeastern part of the United States – traditionally a bastion of conservatism and homophobic ‘family values’ – Blue River, an elite private boarding school, prided itself on being ahead of the cultural curve, a model of progressivism both socially and educationally. I sat on a small sofa across from John, shuffling through photographs of heterosexist graffiti scrawled with permanent black marker across the dorm room doors of two Blue River students. ‘She should be here any moment,’ John said. ‘And I hope when she arrives we can put all of this behind us.’ Susan, one of the targets of the graffiti and an organizer among the school’s LGBT students, had lobbied John and other upper-level school administrators for permission to initiate a formal student organization, tentatively called PRIDE, to fight homopho- bia and heterosexism at Blue River. When I asked her a few days before the meeting about the dean’s reaction to her request, she sighed. ‘The dean cares,’ Susan replied. ‘I know he does. But caring is not the same thing as understanding. He said he’d support PRIDE, but only if we changed it into a diversity appreciation club – only if we agreed not to limit it to lesbian and gay issues.’ ‘What do you think about that idea?’ I asked. ‘I think I’m tired of being appreciated,’ she answered. ‘And how can we be appreciated, anyway, when we have to hide who we are just to be safe?’ When Susan arrived at John’s office, I invited both her and John to share their most recent thoughts on the heterosexist graffiti, the larger problem of heterosex- ism at Blue River, and the anti-heterosexist student group. Susan read from a list of carefully crafted recommendations composed by PRIDE earlier that morning. They requested support to continue developing PRIDE in their own image, not as an apolitical diversity appreciation club. They suggested, and volunteered to coor- dinate, a professional development workshop on LGBT issues for Blue River’s staff. They asked, as well, for more transparency in the school’s handling of the graffiti incident, sharing their concern that similar incidents had been ‘swept under the carpet’ by administrators and teachers. ‘Speaking from my own experience,’ Susan concluded, ‘it seems to be easier to be homophobic here than to be a lesbian. Isn’t that backwards, especially at a school that sells itself as progressive and diverse?’ John listened attentively, scribbling a few notes. He agreed that professional devel- opment was a good idea, but balked at the other two requests. ‘This is a community issue, isn’t it?’ he asked. ‘My sense is that all of this would be best resolved through D o w n l o a d e d B y : [ G o r s k i , P a u l ] A t : 1 1 : 5 9 1 0 J u l y 2 0 0 9 88 P.C. Gorski dialogue and intercultural respect. And how can we encourage intercultural respect when we endorse an exclusive student organization?’ After pausing for a moment, John continued, ‘This is a slippery slope – the student organization. What will we do when a group of our more conservative Christian students want us to support an exclusively heterosexual club?’ ‘I’ve been at this school for three years,’ Susan answered, ‘and I’ve always felt like a stranger here. So you’ll tell them what I’m telling you: this whole school is an exclu- sive heterosexual club. We’re just trying to carve out a little breathing room and you won’t even allow us to do that.’ * * * The problem at Blue River High School, like that at most every school I have visited, whether in India, Colombia, the USA, or anywhere else, is not a lack of commitment to intercultural education among its leaders. They are committed, and quite passionately, to intercultural education. In fact, I cannot recall a single instance in which I have asked a school administrator whether or not she or he was committed to equity or diversity or intercultural education or multiculturalism – and I always ask this question – without being answered with an emphatic yes! One of today’s key discourses among intercultural educators in many parts of the world focuses on something called the ‘achievement gap’ – differences in levels of educational achievement, usually measured narrowly with standardized test scores, between a society’s privileged and oppressed communities. My purpose, and the purpose of this special issue of Intercultural Education, is to point to a different gap which, as I have argued previously in this journal (Gorski 2006, 2008), is, or at least ought to be, more fundamental to the intercultural education discourse. It is not a test score gap or one related to educational attainment. Rather, it is a gap of conscious- ness, a deepening fissure distinguishing the ways in which the most privileged among us prefer to conceptualize intercultural education – ‘This is a community issue, calling for dialogue and intercultural respect’ – and the ways in which the most oppressed of us define the problem that intercultural education should aim to resolve: ‘This whole school is an exclusive heterosexual club.’ This, I believe, is the fundamental gap in our discourse and a threat to the future of authentic intercultural practice in education – the gap distinguishing an overly-simplistic interpersonal (can’t we all just get along?) approach to intercultural education from a systemic approach that insists, first and foremost, on the construction of an equitable and just world. I also believe, however unfortunate, that intercultural education as a field and movement remains, for the most part, in the control of people and organizations who share John’s enthusiasm for ‘diversity’ but lack the conviction to address, in any seri- ous and systemic way, the grave injustices experienced by many of those we invite into interpersonal-intercultural festivities. As a result, most intercultural practice and scholarship, while focusing on cross-cultural relations, respecting differences, conflict resolution, and learning about this or that identity group, stops short of demanding a world free of injustice. Notice, for example, John’s focus on resolving the conflict rather than eliminating the injustice. This, to me, is the epitome of privilege: construct- ing a supposedly progressive movement in a way that requires disenfranchised people to build relationships and resolve conflict with people by whom they are oppressed while ignoring their oppression. I often tell my students – predominantly present and D o w n l o a d e d B y : [ G o r s k i , P a u l ] A t : 1 1 : 5 9 1 0 J u l y 2 0 0 9 Intercultural Education 89 future teachers – that the most critical question we can ask in any examination of social or political action is, to whose benefit and at whose expense? And so, when we practice an intercultural education that values inter-gender peace rather than gender equity, racial harmony rather than racial justice, immigrant acculturation rather than immigrant rights, we must ask ourselves: to whose benefit and at whose expense? This themed issue of Intercultural Education represents one organized attempt to respond to this gap of consciousness by highlighting the scholarship of intercultural educators whose work foregrounds equity, social justice, and human rights rather than cultural understanding and intercultural relationships. Despite coming from a variety of sociopolitical contexts and disciplines, they share a determination to ask critical questions about what is and what could be in intercultural education. They insist that authentic intercultural practice begins with – indeed cannot exist without – the decon- struction of power, privilege, oppression, and the consciousness, or lack of conscious- ness, that these conditions engender in the oppressor and the oppressed. They demand of us contoured analyses of day-to-day educational goings-on such as John’s interac- tion with Susan, not as a way to understand simplistic variants in culture, but to prepare us to help transgress apolitical models of intercultural education that, despite good intentions, run the risk of exacerbating existing injustices. And they invite us to consider how we might funnel deeper levels of intercultural consciousness into socially transformative educational and social activism. We begin with an exploration of critical media literacy as a building block of multicultural education by Paul R. Carr and Brad J. Porfilio. They argue that the future of social justice consciousness relies upon a computer and media literacy that tran- scends ‘tolerance’ and ‘respect.’ In her contribution to this special issue, Jane Quin describes the Trajectory Model, which she uses in South Africa to engage teachers in a reflective assessment of their socializations within oppressive societies. Andria K. Wisler offers a critical take on an oft-identified goal of intercultural education: conflict resolution. She advocates for an approach to conflict resolution that foregrounds social justice concerns and, as a result, encourages democratic global consciousness. Contextualizing intercultural education and critiquing reductionist practices in intercultural development programs, François V. Tochon and A. Cendel Karaman apply a critical-interpretive systems approach to intercultural education. The result is a re-conceptualization of ‘intercultural reasoning’ that insists upon social justice and considers the sociopolitical context of education. Azadeh F. Osanloo argues that authentic civic education must be grounded in crit- ical thinking skills and dialogues that span various public spheres. Osanloo describes universal elements critical to education that is ‘civically responsible,’ focusing partic- ular attention on human rights education. Using grounded theory, Maryan Koehler shares her research on immigration and integration policy for adult newcomers in the Netherlands. Particularly, Koehler discusses the implications of her finding that policymakers highlight ‘assimilation’ as an important element of integration. Chavella T. Pittman’s study raises questions about a common misperception – that changes in attitude regarding multiculturalism necessarily lead to changes in behavior and action. She turns this approach on its head, suggesting an approach to multicul- tural education that focuses on behavior change. D o w n l o a d e d B y : [ G o r s k i , P a u l ] A t : 1 1 : 5 9 1 0 J u l y 2 0 0 9 90 P.C. Gorski Finally, Lorraine Beveridge and Julie Hinde McLeod take on the misperception that our youngest students are incapable of critical consciousness in their description of a literature-based primary school action learning project in Australia. References Gorski, P.C. 2006. Complicity with conservatism: The de-politicizing of multicultural and intercultural education. Intercultural Education 17, no. 2: 163–77. Gorski, P.C. 2008. Good intentions are not enough: A decolonizing intercultural education. Intercultural Education 19, no. 6: 515–25. Paul C. Gorski George Mason University, USA gorski@edchange.org D o w n l o a d e d B y : [ G o r s k i , P a u l ] A t : 1 1 : 5 9 1 0 J u l y 2 0 0 9 work_5tkzdqcetjeb5fihfk7dghj2fi ---- Untitled Edinburgh Research Explorer On climate matters Citation for published version: Cripps, E 2016, 'On climate matters: Offsetting, population, and justice', Midwest Studies In Philosophy, vol. 40, no. 1, pp. 114-128. https://doi.org/10.1111/misp.12050 Digital Object Identifier (DOI): 10.1111/misp.12050 Link: Link to publication record in Edinburgh Research Explorer Document Version: Peer reviewed version Published In: Midwest Studies In Philosophy Publisher Rights Statement: This is the peer reviewed version of the following article: Cripps, E. (2016), On Climate Matters: Offsetting, Population, and Justice. Midwest Stud Philos, 40: 114–128, which has been published in final form at https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/full/10.1111/misp.12050. This article may be used for non-commercial purposes in accordance with Wiley Terms and Conditions for Self-Archiving. General rights Copyright for the publications made accessible via the Edinburgh Research Explorer is retained by the author(s) and / or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing these publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Take down policy The University of Edinburgh has made every reasonable effort to ensure that Edinburgh Research Explorer content complies with UK legislation. If you believe that the public display of this file breaches copyright please contact openaccess@ed.ac.uk providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 06. Apr. 2021 https://doi.org/10.1111/misp.12050 https://doi.org/10.1111/misp.12050 https://www.research.ed.ac.uk/portal/en/publications/on-climate-matters(f285d3b1-da27-4d4b-8af9-e72c43570d32).html 1 On Climate Matters: Offsetting, Population, & Justice1 Elizabeth Cripps [Forthcoming in Midwest Studies in Philosophy] In Climate Matters (2012), John Broome defends a stringent individual duty of justice to reduce one’s net carbon footprint to zero. He argues, moreover, that this can be fulfilled without radical lifestyle changes, by offsetting. These are provocative and, in their different ways, likely to be unpopular claims. However, this paper will argue that Broome’s conclusions are less controversial, in two key ways, than they might be. On offsetting and on the ethics of adding people, Broome’s own arguments lead further than he explicitly goes. One of these would put him in extremely problematic territory; both serve to highlight an underlying difficulty with his account of the moral situation of the individual emitter. For Broome, individual emissions cause harm. If you live a ‘normal’ life in a rich country, ‘your lifetime emissions will wipe out [very roughly] more than six months of healthy human life’ (2012: 74). This loss is spread across the millions of victims of climate change, so thinly that the difference any given emitter makes to each victim is imperceptible. However, it adds up across the victims. Moreover, each contribution combines with those of billions of other emitters, resulting in very great suffering by very many people. Since it is wrong to harm others, each of us has a clear-cut duty to reduce our net emissions to zero. This is a duty of justice2 and takes priority over many other duties. In particular, it takes priority over duties of goodness – duties ‘to try and improve the world’ (2012: 50) – which, in the climate change case, are duties to put pressure on our 1 Thanks to Holly Lawford-Smith and Paul Bou-Habib for detailed comments on this paper. It has also benefited from feedback at a Climate Matters workshop, University of Essex, November 2014, especially from John Broome. I am also grateful to Bou-Habib, organiser of the workshop, the editors of Midwest Studies in Philosophy, and of course Broome himself for this opportunity to comment on a work as practically important and politically timely as it is philosophically engaging. 2 Duties ‘owed by one person to another particular person, or… people’ (Broome 2012: 52). 2 governments to act (2012: 81). (Governments, unlike individuals, have primarily duties of goodness to tackle the overall problem (2012: 64-68).3) At this stage, the affluent reader might be feeling rather uncomfortable. But it turns out that fulfilling this stringent individual duty is considerably easier than we might fear. According to Broome, individuals can fulfil this duty of justice either by cutting their own emissions or by bringing about comparable emissions reductions elsewhere. This might be by carbon removal or preventative offsetting. This latter involves funding projects to reduce others’ emissions, perhaps exploiting energy efficiency technology (2012: 87-89). This option, which allows affluent individuals to ‘buy’ themselves out of changing their habits, raises objections enough.4 However, these are not the focus of this paper. Instead, I argue that in defending preventative offsetting, Broome opens the door to other ways of ‘cancelling out’ one’s own emissions: by funding green technology research, by promoting climate change-mitigating action in other ways, or – possibly – by funding adaptation (Section I). Moreover, on his account of un-offset individual emissions as individual injustices, the decision to have a child is also an injustice (Section II). Finally, (Section III) I will question Broome’s characterisation of the relationship between individual emitters and the collective harm done through climate change. Given that any perceptible harm to victims results from the combination of many individual emissions, it is not clear that individuals have an exclusive or primary duty of justice to stop or negate their individual emissions, rather than try to bring about a collective-level change, nor – if they do – why such duties should automatically take priority over duties of goodness. In concluding, I will briefly indicate how loosening these assumptions can reinforce the expanded account of offsetting, and take some of the sting out of concerns about the implications for individual procreative decision-making. 3 Although they also have obligations of justice, Broome sees these as limited, in the climate change case, by the non-identity problem. His claim is that governments do not harm future individuals through high emissions policies, because without those policies those particular individuals would not come into existence (2012: 61-63). However, this paper will focus on his treatment of individuals and so barely touch on his also significant contribution to the debate on governmental climate duties. 4 E.g. Hyams and Fawcett 2013; Jamieson 2014; Sagoff 2014; Spiekermann 2013. 3 I. OFFSETTING As we have seen, Broome thinks each of us has an individual duty of justice to achieve zero net carbon footprint, which we can fulfil by offsetting. This can take two forms: removing equivalent carbon from the atmosphere, for example by planting trees, or preventing equivalent emissions elsewhere, for example by funding renewable energy projects in the developing world (2012: 85-89). To reiterate, I will not debate whether it is morally acceptable to offset at all, and particularly whether it is so to use preventative offsetting, rather than make lifestyle changes. Rather, this section makes a conditional point: if preventative offsetting is a legitimate way to fulfil this stringent duty of individual justice, so too – potentially – are three other courses of action. The first is offsetting by funding research into ‘green’ technology. The second is offsetting by promoting action on mitigation. This could involve: a) direct, personal influence on the emissions of individuals or small groups close to you or b) influencing government or international policy. The third is offsetting by funding adaptation. Briefly, the reasoning on the first two is as follows. If it is acceptable to offset individual emissions by funding the use of ‘green’ technology to reduce emissions elsewhere, why not also by making more such technology available, bringing about further cuts? Equally, if it is justifiable to continue your own carbon-laden lifestyle so long you fund other people to emit less, why not if you can persuade others to emit less, or bring about policy changes to require everyone to do so? On offsetting by adaptation, the argument rests on the fact that there is more than one way of protecting persons from climate change: curbing the emissions that cause the physical changes to the atmosphere (mitigation) or adapting humans and their environment so that such warming would not undermine central interests.5 At the collective level, both of these are necessary (e.g. Caney 2009: 86-89). However, for current purposes the focus is on the individual emitter: it is the ultimate harm to victims doing the moral work for Broome, so if that harm is prevented, why isn’t this an acceptable way of offsetting? 5 A third possibility, geoengineering, is not discussed here. 4 Suppose, by way of analogy, I want to throw loud Friday night parties but the noise would distress my neighbour. To avoid injustice, I could refrain altogether. If like Broome we accept the legitimacy of preventative offsetting, I could throw my parties but pay the students living on my neighbour’s other side from holding the even louder ones that they would otherwise have had every Saturday night.6 Finally, I could soundproof my walls.7 If anything, the third option looks less morally dubious than the second. The analogy to the third, in the emissions case, is adaptation. There are major objections to this three-fold expansion of offsetting.8 These are uncertain methods. How can the individual be sure (or sure enough) that sufficient harm will be prevented? Even if it is, will it be prevented to exactly the same people as our individual emissions would have harmed? An individual cannot generally justify harming person A by benefiting person B. Indeed, at first sight, the suggestions might look not only problematic, but morally outrageous. The parallel would be with geoengineering, where Stephen Gardiner (2013: 22- 24) compares us, as a generation, with ‘Wayne’. Wayne continually cheats on his wife, exposing her to risk of STDs. He attempts to justify this by investing a few dollars in a company attempting to cure HIV: a very risky enterprise that may not succeed in producing a cure at all, let alone in one which can save his wife. And if this looks problematically speculative, how much more so does appeal to an individual’s chance of influencing either policy or other individuals to cut emissions sufficiently to cancel out her own carbon footprint? In response, I would reiterate that my claim is strictly conditional: not that these are acceptable ways to fulfil strict individual duties of justice, but that if preventative offsetting is a legitimate response to emissions harms, there is no principled reason not to go further. With this in mind, let us begin with the general worry about uncertainty. As Broome acknowledges, preventative 6 I am, of course, making certain assumptions: that my neighbour makes no difference between Friday and Saturday nights and that the students put a lower value on being deprived of entertainment, perhaps because they are poorer. (Precisely this latter point brings out part of the moral unease associated with offsetting. See e.g. Caney (2010: 203-12) on emissions trading.) 7 I could also try to compensate my neighbour. Broome seems prepared to countenance compensation as a means of fulfilling duties of justice (2012: 56-57, 78-81). However this, in moral terms, looks second best, just as it does at the collective level, though it will undoubtedly be necessary as part of a fair collective response (Caney 2009: 86-89). 8 A preliminary difficulty is that of calculating likely reductions, but this is not unique to my suggestions (Broome 2012: 85, 89). 5 offsetting may also be ineffective. He advocates overestimating what is required, to be on the safe side (2012: 87-9). Indeed, even carbon removal offsetting is not certain to bring about exactly the necessary reduction in emissions. Rather than a clear contrast between options – a straightforward cancelling out of one’s emissions, on the one hand, and uncertainty about whether one had done so, on the other – we are faced with a continuum along which there are different levels of uncertainty attached to different offsetting options. The only certainty is not emitting in the first place. Thus, rather than ruling out some means of offsetting altogether, an appropriate response might be to overestimate more and more what is needed, as one moves further along the spectrum.9 There are, moreover, a number of ways in which offsetting by green technology research and by promotion can be made more or less uncertain, while offsetting by adaptation, like preventative offsetting, could be a matter of funding the use of established technology. With green technology research, the individual could spread her investment, provided it is significant enough, over different projects. On offsetting by promotion, the objection would be that most individuals are highly unlikely to make any real difference to policy, try as they might by subscribing to Greenpeace or Friends of the Earth, signing e-petitions, marching on international summits, and so on. However, some individuals do have very great influence, with a potential impact much more than equivalent to a lifetime’s individual emissions. (Whether they could achieve this in practice without cutting their own emissions is, of course, another question: there remains the danger that they will be perceived to be hypocritical, undermining their efforts (Cripps 2013: 152-3).) True, many of those have this influence because they hold positions of power in current state or interstate institutions, and as such should be considered separately from private individuals. But not all those with potentially enormous influence are currently involved in government. Some have become role models for other reasons and could change behaviour on such a mass scale as indirectly to change policy. Others lead non-governmental 9 This could be very costly, giving no incentive for individuals to do it. However, it is worth establishing in theory whether other means of offsetting could satisfy individual duties of justice, because carbon removal or preventative offsetting could become more expensive and individual emission cuts harder. 6 organisations such as corporations or religious organisations. It is not so straightforward to draw a neat line between ‘powerless’ individuals, on the one hand, and all-powerful governments, on the other. Recall, too, that there are two levels of offsetting by promotion. Anyone with influence on relatively small groups of others – teachers, local community leaders, journalists – might be able to ‘cancel out’ their own emissions by provoking emissions cuts by those others, or at local policy level. (Again, of course, subject to the perceived hypocrisy objection.) Let us turn, then, to the second worry: even if the same amount of harm is prevented, it may not be harm to the same people. Depriving one person of six months of life cannot be justified by prolonging another’s life by six months. (On the common sense morality upheld by Broome, it cannot be justified by giving six months to ten others.) But why should this apply more to offsetting by technology research or promotion than to preventative offsetting? The idea behind preventative offsetting is that one can spare the victims and so fulfil one’s duty of justice by cancelling out one’s own emissions through reductions elsewhere. These two are simply alternative ways of doing that. If the concern is with those who could be harmed as a result of the time lag between individual emissions and any offsetting reduction, this is a serious worry, but one which is not unique to my proposals. The same applies to many kinds of preventative offsetting (some projects will have a very long gestation period) and may not – if one’s influence on others is rapid enough – apply to some kinds of offsetting by promotion. If I could get away with it, I could give a rousing talk one afternoon which prompted twenty regular commuters to ditch their cars for bikes, then fly off to the South of France on holiday, safe in the knowledge that my day had reduced emissions by more than it had increased it. (Again, remember that I am not defending this, all-things-considered, but simply pointing out that it is another way of ensuring that, for any emissions I cause, I also cause an equivalent or greater reduction elsewhere.) On offsetting by adaptation, however, there are some more specific difficulties. The idea behind the other options is that so long so you don’t cause extra overall emissions in the atmosphere, no-one will be harmed by your actions. Here, the suggestion is, instead, that the individual could somehow 7 intervene to shield victims from the physical changes associated with any increased emissions. But she can hardly be sure that those people whom her adaptation aid protects will be the same ones whom her emissions will have harmed. I have some responses to this worry, but they may remain inadequate until supplemented by Section III. Firstly, preventative offsetting is not entirely immune to such difficulties. Even allowing for overestimating in response to uncertainty about whether emissions will be reduced enough elsewhere, some harm to some victims could still slip through the net. This is because of a combination of potential time lags and the impossibility of being certain one has overestimated sufficiently. In other words, accepting even preventative offsetting means not assigning absolute priority to ensuring that no victims are left harmed a result of your actions.10 Indeed, taking concerns about time lags to their natural conclusions, adaptation might be the closest some polluters can get to negating their own emissions. Consider those who are now elderly and have been emitting all their life. What would Broome’s justice require of them? This is not clear, but it is reasonable to assume that he would think they should offset all past emissions. However, some victims already live with the effects of climate change. The early, un-offset emissions of those still living could have contributed to this, and it is a suffering which cannot now be prevented by mitigation but might be eased by adaptation aid. (Taking this further, compensation aid could be required, where central interests have already been undermined.) Finally, what each individual causes are imperceptible harms to each of the many victims of climate change, rather than perceptible losses caused by each emitter to any given individuals. This, I suggest, could justify responding by spreading adaptation aid also across as many as possible. But this relies to arguments that will not be filled out until Section III. This completes, for now, my discussion of offsetting. It might seem that my conditional claim – if preventative offsetting is an acceptable way to fulfil individual duties of justice, so too are these other speculative ways of stepping 10 Broome does not rule out a ‘surrogate compensation’ approach, compensating large numbers of people as a proxy for those actually harmed (2012: 80-81). This would be vulnerable to the same objection. 8 between one’s emissions and harm – is ultimately a case against preventative offsetting: almost a reductio ad absurdum. But my aim is at once less destructive and more critical than that. Section III will identify some limitations of Broome’s account of the connection between individual duty-bearers and the harm done by climate change. These accepted, I will suggest that at least some of my suggestions could be as appropriate a response to carbon emissions as – and arguably more appropriate than – cutting one’s own carbon footprint, even by conventional means. For now, however, I turn to a second way in which what Broome explicitly says about individual climate duties stops short of where his own arguments should take him. II. THE INJUSTICE OF ADDING PEOPLE Broome is adamant that parents should not expect others to pick up the tab for their decision to have children (2012: 71-72). My contention, taking him into still more controversial territory,11 is that he is committed to condemning voluntary, foreseeable procreation as an injustice. In having a child, parents create not only a new person, with her own emissions, but the prospect of a whole line of descendants, all emitting. A number of objections are likely. One is that parents do not harm so long as they have fewer than replacement rate children. However, Broome requires zero carbon footprint, not merely keeping below some ‘fair share’ emissions threshold (2012: 79). Moreover, even if parents have only one or two children, the stage of life at which they have them affects total emissions: the more the overlap between generations, the greater the impact. Thus, on Broome’s own account, there are reasons to reject this objection. Even accepting it, however, the argument would hold for more than replacement rate children. (This is a less counterintuitive conclusion, although one still likely to raise hackles.) A second objection is that the cost of not having children is too great to require anyone to refrain. A parent’s relationship with her child can make a central contribution to a full human life: one not substitutable by other goods 11 Controversial, but not altogether uncharted, e.g. Young (2001). 9 (e.g. Brighouse and Swift 2006; Conly 2005). Thus, to ask someone to give up the opportunity could be to demand a huge sacrifice.12 However, on the strict common sense morality on which Broome draws, we must not (as individuals) do serious harm even if the cost to us of avoiding it is high. He specifies that ‘[j]ustice does not prohibit you from doing harms you cannot help’ (2012: 59) but most of us, at least in the affluent world, can ‘help’ having children, albeit at an emotional cost. I would not generally be justified in cutting off your arm even if that were the only way to save my own.13 If our intuitions pull against such a hard line in cases like climate change, where the harm results from the combination of many actions none of which do perceptible harm on their own, then perhaps we have reason to doubt whether such contributions really do count as harms, or injustices, in the same way as ‘standard’ individual violations of that widely-shared prohibition on doing serious harm to other persons, the no-harm principle. This will be taken up in Section III. In any case, it is more plausible that we have a central interest in being able to have and experience a relationship with a child, than that we need to be able to have unlimited children in order to flourish. (Conly 2005: 107; Cripps 2016a: 6- 8). Thus, on a modified view, it would still be an injustice to have more than one or two children. A third objection to the claim that Broome must consider procreation an injustice is that overall emissions will not increase if the child’s net emissions – and those of any future descendants – are zero. Thus, a parent can avoid injustice by guaranteeing this. But this is problematic. Children will grow up and make their own decisions. Parents can educate and encourage them, but they can’t guarantee that they will not emit or procreate and they can’t offset for unlimited 12 Whether this requires biological parenting is another question, but it cannot be taken for granted that it does not. 13 A related objection – that interference with procreation would violate a human right, grounded in this interest in procreating – is misplaced. The discussion here is entirely at the individual level. This paper neither makes, nor accuses Broome of making, a case for policy to enforce restraint from procreation. Indeed, the argument is perfectly compatible with a collective or state duty to bring about a better situation in which individuals can procreate without committing injustice. 10 emissions. Even if they could do so for this child, they could not do so for their potential descendants.14 A version of this objection appeals to the urgency of the collective challenge. Given that limiting risks across central areas of concern will require zero overall emissions by the end of the century (IPCC 2014: 18), effective collective action would have to ensure that future generations have no carbon emissions. If parents can take this for granted, they needn’t consider their future children as future emitters. But, of course, this is precisely what they cannot do. Potential parents, like all of us, face the sad probability that the necessary collective action won’t be achieved. In that case, it is reasonable to assume that the already great harm would be worsened by greater ongoing emissions. (The alternative is an implausibly all-or-nothing view on which, once this opportunity to mitigate sufficiently has been missed, the situation will be so dire anyway that it no longer matters what our combined emissions are: the kind of reasoning that says one might as well light a cigarette once the house is on fire.) Then, on Broome’s account, individual carbon footprints would still count as harms. Perhaps the point is not that the parent can’t guarantee that her child will not emit, or have children in her turn, but that it will be that child’s choice to do so, and so her (not her parents’) responsibility. After all, we do not generally hold criminals’ parents responsible for their crimes simply because they produced them. However, children may not actually have that option, given continued failure to act collectively on climate change. Zero net emissions is a realistic option for Broome’s current affluent readers only because of the availability and affordability of offsets. Whether or not these future adults could avoid emitting – and I am not suggesting that they will not be responsible for any of their emissions choices – they can, on current patterns, be predicted to have a significant carbon footprint. The analogy with the criminal fails: most children will not grow up to be thieves or murderers, but parents in this unique situation create the probability of 14 A rival suggestion would be ‘offsetting’ by funding others not to have children. This might seem a natural extension of the tradable procreation rights sometimes mooted (De La Croix and Gosseries 2009). However, it seems doubly problematic. On a one-for-one basis it would be ineffective: any such cuts in population growth are likely to be in the developing world, where per capita emissions are dramatically lower. Moreover, whatever moral concerns arise regarding emissions offsetting in general multiply a hundredfold in this peculiarly morally charged context. 11 emissions by creating the agent who will probably go on to cause them (including by having children in their turn). They knowingly run a high risk of increasing overall emissions. And for Broome, significant risks of harms count as injustices (2012: 79). However, one important caveat must be acknowledged, regarding parents’ responsibility for emitting descendants. In general, as strings of consequences grow, it becomes less plausible to assign moral responsibility for all those consequences to those whose actions started the chain. This is partly because of other agents’ actions and natural events in between, partly because we standardly only hold persons responsible for consequences reasonably foreseeable when they acted. While it is reasonable for a parent to expect that her children will a) emit and b) have children who will emit, it may not be so reasonable to assume this of her more distant descendants. On a), our ability to predict technological progress, and/or collective-level policy, is too limited to extrapolate current trends beyond a generation or two. On b), the chain of procreation relies on certain decisions (and abilities) at every generation. There is also the chance, at each stage, of some destructive external event. Generally speaking, it seems reasonable to draw the line for any responsibility for future emissions (at the least) at the point at which it becomes less likely that someone will have further emitting descendants than that they will not. Of course, it will be almost impossible to pinpoint when this is. It will also vary significantly according to how many children someone has. The argument of this section would hold, however, for at least a few generations. Another objection to my expansion of Broome’s view appeals to parents’ influence over their children. The suggestion is that those potential parents who are likely to take seriously a moral injunction not to procreate are also those who would be likely to bring up their children to be environmentally aware. The claim then, would be that these are precisely the kind of people who ought to be peopling the next generation. This can be rejected. Recall that Broome is concerned narrowly with the individual injustice of having a positive net carbon footprint. The argument would have to be that ‘right-minded’ parents could produce children so personally conscientious and so effective at motivating others that it would be 12 better to have them than not, in overall emissions terms. But parental influence, while important, cannot do everything. Moreover, many who currently consider themselves ‘green’ have failed to achieve a zero carbon footprint. It would hardly, then, be realistic, to expect one’s potential child to go so far beyond this as to have, in effect, a negative footprint. And while we undoubtedly need exceptional leaders to turn the tide of collective lethargy on climate change, no parent could reasonably gamble on her own child being one. A final objection appeals to Broome’s rejection of the intuition of neutrality: the view that we can be morally neutral about the number of flourishing people brought into the world whilst considering it morally important that whoever does exist can flourish (2012: 170-88).15 This could imply a duty of goodness to procreate, so long as the presence of an extra person did not reduce overall happiness more than her own would add to it. At the individual level, this can quickly be rejected. On Broome’s common sense morality, duties of justice have priority for the private individual. However, important related questions are raised. If there were a duty to refrain from having any children, and if all complied with this duty (which is, of course, improbable), the consequences would be devastating: even more so, at least from an anthropocentric viewpoint, than those of everyone failing to comply with other climate duties. Again, on the Broomian model, this doesn’t change the individual duty. However, is hard not to see this itself as reason to revisit either the absolute priority of justice over goodness at the individual level, or the focus on climate change as a matter of direct individual responsibility for harm. III. CLIMATE CHANGE AND INDIVIDUAL HARM So far, two unacknowledged implications of Broome’s argument have been outlined. These might be left constructive amendments to his project, at least if the procreative duty of justice could be consistently interpreted as one to stop at 15 I will not engage with Broome’s argument for this rejection. Nor is it within the scope of this paper to address what else he says about population in the context of governmental duties: his favourable mention of tying state emissions quotas to fixed population levels (2012: 71. See Cripps 2016b on the latter.) 13 one or two children, rather than not have any at all. But I will not leave it at that, because there remains an underlying concern about Broome’s characterisation of individual’s moral relationship to the harm caused through climate change. This is a challenge which, in their different ways, both the previous sections press on us. For clarity, let us separate his view into four points: 1. That, as affluent individuals, we are each causally responsible for harms through our own emissions, amounting to six months’ loss of human life. 2. That this is the kind of harm that violates the individual no-harm principle and counts as an injustice. 3. That, accordingly, each of us has a duty of justice to stop or negate those individual emissions 4. That this duty takes priority over any duties of goodness we have, such as our duty to promote government action on climate change (2012: 54-57, 64- 68, 74-81). I will begin with some independent concerns about point (4), then address the first three, before returning briefly to (4). Broome’s view is that governments can legitimately prioritise goodness over justice (so long as they compensate where possible), but individuals can rarely do so. In the climate change context, this is at least partly because governments, unlike individuals, can make a very great difference to what happens at the collective level (2012: 64-69). I have already suggested that, as regards some individuals, this depiction of powerlessness may be a mistake. I now want to make a more general point: in focusing only on what governments can do and on what individuals can do as individuals (cutting their own emissions as a matter of justice or lobbying their government as a matter of goodness), there is a danger of neglecting a third possibility. This is what can, and in the climate change case can only, be achieved through collective action at a level at which there is as yet no effective collective agency. This is important in at least two ways. Firstly, even individual governments may be powerless without cooperation with others (Gardiner 2011: 95-96). This 14 might involve a global agreement (for example, the cap and trade scheme suggested by Broome (2012: 68-72)) and/or establishing a global institution. Secondly, potential groupings of individuals, beyond our current groupings into states, could make a very great difference indeed. This might be by collectively demanding global institutional change or through global citizens’ activism networks, changing emissions patterns (Jamieson 2011: 36). Thus, the possibility arises of a shared duty requiring everyone (or all affluent persons) to cooperate to achieve global climate action. Given the extraordinary moral salience of that end, a case might be made for prioritising individual duties to bring about such cooperation over any individual duty to neutralise individual emissions in isolation, so long as the ultimate collective scheme also compensated any victims of injustice where necessary and possible.16 Now let us turn to points (1) and (2). My objection is not to Broome’s calculations, based on World Health Organisation estimates of the toll of climate change. It is to his doing them at all: to the reduction of an aggregate harm to the individual level. We can get at this concern in two ways: resisting point (1) by questioning his ‘divvying up’ of total impact to conclude that each contributor has effectively caused climate change amounting to a six months’ loss of human life; or rejecting (2) by resisting the summing of imperceptible harms across different victims to make that six months’ loss a violation of the individual no- harm principle. On the challenge to (1), which has been made elsewhere,17 I will simply flag up the distinction between a number of individuals performing actions harmful in themselves which add up to greater harm, and a number of individuals performing actions which make no difference at all in isolation but, in combination, bring about serious harm. To assess this latter as individually- caused harm, the argument must appeal to the chance that any given individual contribution will trigger some threshold at which harm is increased (Hiller 2011; 16 As clarified elsewhere (Cripps 2013: 115-39), I am not suggesting that individuals shouldn’t cut their own emissions. The point here is that reducing them to zero is not necessarily the only or the best way to fulfil duties relating to such collective harm. In practice, of course, the two ends might not conflict. Cutting individual emissions might a way to promote wider action. If it were not, affluent individuals could use offsetting to do both. However, if either offsetting or restraint were costlier, it could pull against promoting collective action. 17 Jamieson 2014. See also Cripps 2013: 119-24; Maltais 2013; Nolt 2011. 15 Kagan 2011): of being, as it were, that additional straw which breaks the camel’s back. Instead, I will begin my current critique at (2). For the sake of argument, I will accept Broome’s claim that the individual makes some difference to what happens at the collective level, concede his six-months figure as a reasonable estimate, and focus on whether this violates the moral injunction against doing serious harm to any other person. If not, this could still be an ‘injustice’. However, it would be one for a different reason than that it violates the individual no-harm principle, and so need not automatically give rise to the same duties. The issue is this: there is a significant difference between depriving one person of six months of life, and causing the loss of six months of healthy human life spread across so many people that each one loses only the most infinitesimal fraction of a second, which is how Broome characterises the situation (2012: 75- 6). Broome defends his approach as follows: [A] great many minuscule, imperceptible harms add up to a serious harm. If you doubt that, think of the recipients of harm. Each one receives harm from the emissions of billions of people. The amount each receives from each emitter is minuscule and imperceptible. Yet some recipients are already suffering serious harm in total. Some are even being killed by global warming. This shows that adding up vast numbers of miniscule amounts can amount to a serious harm. Similarly, although each emitter harms each recipient only imperceptibly, the amounts add up. (2012: 75-76.) However, this glosses together two ways of summing harms: summing what all the contributors, including me, do to each victim, and summing what I do to each of those affected. The fact that both yield a significant total harm does not show what is needed to invoke the individual no-harm principle: that I cause significant harm to any one person. So long as we think only qua private individual, there remains the objection that what I do doesn’t cause anybody to suffer anything. Thus it is necessary either to accept that an imperceptible harm can violate the no-harm principle,18 or to consider all contributions to serious 18 See Parfit’s ‘Single Torturer’ (1984: 81-2). 16 harm to be individual injustices, regardless of whether they are harmful in themselves. (This amounts, in effect, to picking up where denying (1) would have left us.) In either case, I suggest, the step to (3), above, can be questioned. Consider the possibility that contributions to serious harm count as individual injustices.19 But which contributions, and under what circumstances? It would surely be too restrictive for a code of private morality to rule out all acts which could combine to cause great harms if others also did them. A relevant question must be whether others will or can be expected to do so. But if this sort of ‘injustice’ arises only because of how others act and how the consequences of these actions combine with those of the private individual, must that individual’s exclusive, or even primary, correlative duty be to refrain from performing her own action? Instead, faced with such ‘new harms’, collective action might be needed to fulfil duties of justice (Cripps 2013: 68-77; Lichtenberg 2010). This is in no way to undermine the moral seriousness of the case: each individual must respond appropriately to the situation in which she and others are bringing about a very great harm between them. However, she might do this by promoting collective action to prevent that harm. Even if an imperceptible harm does violate the no-harm principle, grounding a prima facie duty to refrain, this is so far from the classic case of serious, foreseeable individual harm – when individual A kills individual B – as arguably to require revisiting the all-trumping status of the principle. Indeed, given how indirect the link is between the individual actions and any significant harm, it is again unclear why the duty to refrain should be the only or even the primary duty of justice, if other courses of action could contribute more effectively to preventing or redressing that significant, combined harm. It is also unclear, reinforcing the case against (4) above, why any duty to refrain should take priority over any and all duties of goodness. Again, this is in no way to deny that the situation imposes some strong, negatively-grounded moral duty: this is no easy way out for the individual. This completes the case against Broome’s points (1) to (3). Note also that the points just raised can reinforce my tentative conclusions on (4), by taking the 19 This links to an extensive literature. E.g. Cripps 2013: 119-39; Otsuka 1991; Parfit 1984: 67-86; Spiekermann 2014. 17 sting from one probable worry about that view. It is deep-rooted in common sense morality that individuals cannot justify harm to other individuals by doing (even much greater) good in another way. Were my suggestion the general one that individuals might sometimes legitimately prioritise an obligation to promote almost untold collective good over fulfilling duties not to harm, it would have dangerous implications. (What if my duty to bring about collective action on climate change were fulfillable by assassinating oil industry leaders? Would I seriously want to defend this?) However, I hope the distinction remains clear between contributions to combined harms, which are not perceptibly harmful in isolation, and actions which are individually harmful. The points made against (4) are limited to instances of the former. In the light of what has just been said, I can better indicate why some measures proposed in Section I are morally viable alternatives to conventional offsetting, and suggest that some, at least, might be more appropriate even than individual emissions cuts. Recall Gardiner’s Wayne, who exposes his wife to the risk of STDs and tries to justify himself by investing in uncertain medical research. The analogy fits us depressingly well as a generation or global elite, as we flail around for ever more speculative measures to avoid cutting luxury emissions. But the individual is not Wayne. She and others are causing great harm in combination; she is not directly causing it to any one victim. This situation makes a strong, negative moral claim on her, but one that could be as appropriately or effectively met by funding adaptation or green technology research, both of which counter some of that combined harm, as by preventative offsetting, which does the same. Moreover, some individual investments in adaptation or green technology research could prevent perceptible harm to individual victims (at least if the technology investment involves a big enough contribution, spread widely enough). The individual cannot do this simply by buying carbon removal offsets, or even refraining from individual emissions. In promoting collective action to end the overall harm, the individual could be acting still more appropriately. She would be attempting to broker a collective 18 solution to an injustice which is also, ultimately, collective: to stop us, as a generation, from being Wayne. We might also pick up where Section II left us: with implications highly counterintuitive and, if collectivised, so problematic as to give us prima facie reason to question the view of individual emissions and harm on which they rested. Now that view has indeed been challenged, there is no need to espouse a stringent individual duty to have no children: the focus can legitimately be on promoting the building of a world in which the next generation can thrive without emissions. However, the insight remains that procreative decisions are an important contributor to the overall catastrophe of climate change. The challenge, then, is twofold: to evaluate how the population factor should be incorporated into any collective response (a challenge exacerbated if we accept Broome’s rejection of the intuition of neutrality); and to determine whether any individual duty to refrain from procreating above a certain number of children can be defended either as part of such a collective endeavour or as a necessary part of promoting it. In providing a way around the most extreme implications of Broome’s view of individual justice, I am in no way undermining the paramount importance of this task. References Brighouse, Harry and Swift, Adam (2006), 'Parents' Rights and the Value of the Family', Ethics, 117, 80-108. Broome, John (2012), Climate Matters: Ethics in a warming world, ed. Kwame Anthony Appiah (Amnesty International Global Ethics Series; New York: W. W. Norton) Caney, Simon (2009), 'Climate Change, Human Rights, and Moral Thresholds', in Stephen Humphreys (ed.), Human Rights and Climate Change (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). --- (2010), 'Markets, Morality and Climate Change: What, if Anything, is Wrong with Emissions Trading?' New Political Economy. Conly, Sarah (2005), 'The Right to Procreation: Merits and Limits', American Philosophical Quarterly, 42 (2), 105-15. Cripps, Elizabeth (2013), Climate Change and the Moral Agent: Individual Duties in an Interdependent World (Oxford: Oxford University Press) --- (2016a) 'Climate Change, Population, and Justice: Hard choices to avoid tragic choices', Global Justice: Theory, Practice, Rhetoric, 8 (2), 1-22 19 --- (2016b), 'Population and Environment: The impossible, the impermissible, and the imperative', in Stephen Gardiner and Allen Thompson (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Environmental Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press), DOI: 10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199941339.013.34 De La Croix, David and Gosseries, Axel (2009), 'Population Policy Through Tradable Procreation Entitlements', International Economic Review, 50 (2), 507-42. Gardiner, Stephen M. (2011), A Perfect Moral Storm: The Ethical Tragedy of Climate Change (Oxford & New York: Oxford University Press) --- (2013), 'Geoengineering and Moral Schizophrenia', in Will C. G. Burns and Andrew L. Strauss (eds.), Climate Change Geoengineering: Philosophical Perspectives, Legal Issues, and Governance Frameworks (New York: Cambridge University Press). Gheaus, Anca (2016), 'The Right to Parent and Duties Concerning Future Generations', Journal of Political Philosophy, 24 (1), DOI: 10.1111/jopp.12091 Hiller, Avram (2011), 'Climate Change and Individual Responsibility', The Monist, 94 (3), 349-68. Hyams, Keith and Fawcett, Tina (2013), 'The ethics of carbon offsetting', WIRES Climate Change, (4), 91-98. IPCC (2014), 'IPCC Fifth Assessment Synthesis Report: Summary for Policymakers', in Rajendra K. Pachauri and Leo Meyer (eds.), (Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change). Jamieson, Dale (2011), 'Energy, ethics, and the transformation of nature', in Denis G. Arnold (ed.), The Ethics of Global Climate Change (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 16-37. --- (2014), 'Review of Climate Matters: Ethics in a Warming World', Ethics and International Affairs, 28 (2), 263-5. Kagan, Shelly (2011), 'Do I Make a Difference?' Philosophy and Public Affairs, 39 (2), 105-41. Lichtenberg, Judith (2010), 'Negative Duties, Positive Duties, and the "New Harms"', Ethics, 120 (3), 557-78. Maltais, Aaron (2013), 'Radically non-ideal climate politics and the obligation to at least vote green', Environmental Values, 22 (5), 589-608. Nolt, John (2011), 'How Harmful Are the Average American's Greenhouse Gas Emissions?' Ethics, Policy and Environment 14 (1), 3–10. Otsuka, Michael (1991), 'The Paradox of Group Beneficence', Philosophy and Public Affairs, 20, 132-49. Parfit, Derek (1984), Reasons and Persons (1987 Corrected reprint edn.; Oxford: Clarendon Press) Sagoff, Mark (2014), 'Review of Climate Matters: Ethics in a Warming World', Mind, 123, 194-97. Spiekermann, Kai (2013), 'Buying Low, Flying High: Carbon Offsets and Partial Compliance', Political Studies. --- (2014), 'Small impacts and imperceptible effects: causing harm with others', Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 38, 75-90. Young, Thomas (2001), 'Overconsumption and Procreation: Are they Morally Equivalent?' Journal of Applied Philosophy, 18 (2), 183-92. 20 work_5tx2ancep5dmxdyilma2py6cu4 ---- INVITED SPEAKER PRESENTATION Open Access Global health and global justice Norman Daniels From 7th Postgraduate Forum on Health Systems and Policies Phitsanulok, Thailand. 24-25 June 2013 Most people are concerned about international health inequalities and find them unjust. At the same time, we lack global institutions that can effectively act to reduce these health inequalities, which have various sources. Accordingly, the concern about health inequalities does not by itself support some one of the competing theories of global justice. Yet, many people believe that specific problems increase injustice globally and might be addressed by various measures: the brain drain of health workers from poorer to richer countries, the lack of devel- opment and dissemination of drugs that address the global burden of disease, the high rates of mortality (and morbid- ity) that reflect obvious weaknesses in health systems (e.g. maternal mortality rates), the lack of universal coverage for important health services, the lack of effective global public goods, such as better surveillance systems. I recom- mend an approach to developing an account of global jus- tice that builds on promising solutions to such specific issues, where these solutions build sustainable institutions that address the problems. Published: 29 January 2014 doi:10.1186/1471-2458-14-S1-I1 Cite this article as: Daniels: Global health and global justice. BMC Public Health 2014 14(Suppl 1):I1. Submit your next manuscript to BioMed Central and take full advantage of: • Convenient online submission • Thorough peer review • No space constraints or color figure charges • Immediate publication on acceptance • Inclusion in PubMed, CAS, Scopus and Google Scholar • Research which is freely available for redistribution Submit your manuscript at www.biomedcentral.com/submitCorrespondence: ndaniels@hsph.harvard.edu Harvard University, Cambridge, MA, USA Daniels BMC Public Health 2014, 14(Suppl 1):I1 http://www.biomedcentral.com/1471-2458/14/S1/I1 © 2014 Daniels; licensee BioMed Central Ltd. This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/2.0), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited. The Creative Commons Public Domain Dedication waiver (http:// creativecommons.org/publicdomain/zero/1.0/) applies to the data made available in this article, unless otherwise stated. mailto:ndaniels@hsph.harvard.edu http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/2.0 http://creativecommons.org/publicdomain/zero/1.0/ http://creativecommons.org/publicdomain/zero/1.0/ work_5uckcbzdibarxg2h6tpsu7edpe ---- JETLaw |  | Vanderbilt University Skip to main content Health Protocols Previous Next Return to Campus: Our Plan for Spring 2021 Anchor Down. Step Up. Vanderbilt faculty sharing their expertise on a range of topics related to COVID-19 Vanderbilt Responds to COVID-19 Find information for: Undergraduate Students Graduate and Professional Students International Students Faculty Postdocs Staff Visitors and Suppliers Search frequently asked questions View messages sent to the community Have a question? Return to Campus About Vanderbilt University, located in Nashville, Tenn., is a private research university offering a full range of undergraduate, graduate and professional degrees. Quick Facts History of Vanderbilt Chancellor's Office University Leadership Team Academic Strategic Plan Residential Colleges News and Events Equity, Diversity and Inclusion Key Dates A-Z: About Vanderbilt Campus Map Our City: Nashville Work at VU GlobalVU VU Medical Center Connect with Vanderbilt Facebook Twitter Instagram YouTube Flickr Quick Facts Contact Us More Admissions Previous Next Find Your Major Take a Virtual Tour of Campus Learn more about our Residential Colleges Undergraduate Admissions Graduate / Professional Admissions Disciplines and Majors Residential Colleges Financial Aid and Scholarships Equity, Diversity and Inclusion Key Dates Schedule a Campus Visit Request Information Our City: Nashville Transfer Students International Students A-Z: Admissions Find Your Major More Academics Disciplines and Majors Online Education Programs Academic Calendar University Registrar Course Catalog & Schedule YES - Your Enrollment Services Office of the Provost Residential Colleges Libraries A-Z: Academics Colleges and Schools College of Arts and Science Blair School of Music Divinity School School of Engineering Graduate School Law School School of Medicine School of Nursing Owen Graduate School of Management Peabody College of Education and Human Development Find Your Major More Research Previous Next Vanderbilt scientists sketch rare star system using more than a century of astronomical observations New CRISPR screening technique developed at Vanderbilt leads to discovery of pathway that may be linked to cancer initiation 2020 Tennessee Men’s Health Report Card: Overall improvement, work to be done Vanderbilt-developed obesity treatments will be advanced through collaboration with Soleno Therapeutics Evidence suggests climate whiplash may have more extremes in store for California COVID-19 Information for Researchers Vanderbilt Research Research News @Vanderbilt VU Research Administration VUMC Research Administration Centers and Institutes Undergraduate Research Libraries A-Z: Research Subscribe to our e-newsletter: Research News@Vanderbilt Research News Students Previous Next Tag your photos: #vandygram Tag your photos: #vandygram Tag your photos: #vandygram Tag your photos: #vandygram Career Center Commencement Dean of Students Dining Equity, Diversity and Inclusion Global Education Office Honor System Housing International Students The Ingram Commons Libraries Residential Colleges Student Accounts Student Care Network Student Government Student Handbook Student Organizations Vanderbilt Hustler Apps and Systems YES Brightspace Anchor Link Email Login Mobile App The Hub A-Z: Students Living on Campus The Hub Faculty & Staff Previous Next Dr. Anthony Fauci to deliver 2021 Vanderbilt Graduates Day address Class of 2021 Commencement to be celebrated in person May 15–16; Graduates Day to feature Dr. Anthony Fauci What led to the U.S. Capitol insurrection: Vanderbilt political scientists examine social, psychological, legal foundations of Jan. 6 riot Vanderbilt University spotlights 2020 Service Award recipients Vanderbilt embarks on $55 million renovation and expansion project at the Owen Graduate School of Management Benefits Brightspace Child & Family Center Email Login Equity, Diversity and Inclusion Faculty Gateway (Resources) Faculty Registry Health & Wellness Honor System Human Resources Mobile App myVU (News for Faculty & Staff) Office of Postdoctoral Affairs Shared Governance SkyVU Work at VU A-Z: Faculty A-Z: Staff myVU Faculty Gateway More Alumni & Giving Previous Next Student Hardship Fund created to help students in need Opportunity Vanderbilt provides $1.2 billion in financial aid Vanderbilt launches the Frist Center for Autism and Innovation Alumni programs and resources Find Your Alumni Chapter Reunion Give to Vanderbilt Opportunity Vanderbilt Impact of your gifts Connect with the Alumni Association Vanderbilt Alumni Facebook Vanderbilt Alumni Twitter Vanderbilt Alumni Instagram Vanderbilt YouTube Vanderbilt Alumni Flickr Vanderbilt Alumni LinkedIn Give Now More Athletics Previous Next Student-athlete Abbey Carlson: Engineer and golfer Student-athlete: Kaylann Boyd Student-athlete: Jared Pinkney Student-athlete: The Champions Varsity Sports Intramural Sports Recreation and Wellness Center Commodore Club Commodores Gear Tickets A-Z: Athletics Connect with the Commodores VUCommodores Twitter VUCommodores Facebook VUCommodores Instagram VUCommodores YouTube VUCommodores Pinterest Tickets More JETLaw The Vanderbilt Journal of Entertainment and Technology Law is in the process of creating a new and improved website. We apologize for the temporary inconvenience this may cause in accessing JETLaw content. Our articles are available on both WestLaw and LexisNexis. Alternatively, you can request a past article by emailing our Editor in Chief, Ramon J. Ryan. We are currently accepting submissions for Volume 23 through Scholastica or directly by email at jetl@vanderbilt.edu. Our most recent issue, Volume 23: Issue 1, is available here. Connect with Vanderbilt Facebook Instagram Twitter YouTube LinkedIn Flickr RSS Feed Your Vanderbilt Alumni Current Students Prospective Students International Resources Faculty and Staff Media Medical Center Parents and Family Researchers Sports Fans Visitors and Neighbors Working at Vanderbilt Quick Links University Leadership Residential Colleges News Events Equity, Diversity and Inclusion Finding Your Impact Telling the Vanderbilt Story Nashville, Tennessee 37240 · 615-322-7311 · Contact Us ©  Vanderbilt University · All rights reserved. Site Development: Digital Strategies (Division of Communications) Vanderbilt University is committed to principles of equal opportunity and affirmative action. Accessibility information. Vanderbilt®, Vanderbilt University®, V Oak Leaf Design®, Star V Design® and Anchor Down® are trademarks of The Vanderbilt University work_5wl4sjg62rfq3alm2v2m5e62sa ---- 10.11648.j.ash.20190502.11 Advances in Sciences and Humanities 2019; 5(2): 43-48 http://www.sciencepublishinggroup.com/j/ash doi: 10.11648/j.ash.20190502.11 ISSN: 2472-0941 (Print); ISSN: 2472-0984 (Online) On Cohen’s Critique of Technology and Social Justice Li Yong 1 , Zhang Yi 2 1 Marxist Philosophy Institute, Shanxi University, Taiyuan, China 2 Philosophy, School of Humanities, University of Glasgow, Glasgow, UK Email address: To cite this article: Li Yong, Zhang Yi. On Cohen’s Critique of Technology and Social Justice. Advances in Sciences and Humanities. Vol. 5, No. 2, 2019, pp. 43-48. doi: 10.11648/j.ash.20190502.11 Received: December 6, 2018; Accepted: January 10, 2019; Published: April 12, 2019 Abstract: It is supposed that to be just in society is the intrinsic pursuit of Marxist theory in Marx’s original text. While as the result of historical context, according to Marx, the just society can be realized in a far future. Cohen holds materialism standpoint to illustrate historical materialism creatively by functional explanation in the modern history context. In a new time with much more advanced science and technology, he is keeping going with the route of Marxism for overcoming the technique alienation and argues that in order to realize freedom, equality and justice, appealing to empirical critique of technology and exploration of social theory is essential. The demonstration of that freedom, equality and justice are compatible, which is a cornerstone of practical just social theory. As Cohen is in the analytical tradition, his creative functional explanation presents obvious empiricism and analytical character. He digs out the key of resolving problem of development in moral dimension apart from the materialism, and conducts the argument to attack the political designs, which separates free distribution in market, quality in society, and just spirit from each other. This essay is intended to figure out Cohen’s argument that is based on the traditional Marxism and stand, while points out a new way to help people reach the just society at the much more near future. Keywords: Justice, Functional Explanation, Critique 1. Introduction Marx acknowledged that “only if we accumulate adequate material capital”, then the just could come; while he also located the feasibility into remote ideal. Therefore, Cohen, aiming to modify this thought, try his best to explore a new path, which grantss opportunity for realizing just in social based on current conditions, and provides proofs for its possibility, actuality and feasibility. In Cohen’s mind, we can realize this aim on the current situation by means of combination of technology critique, how to deal with the relationship between technology and human nature, as well as social critique, rethinking whether social system could be running more reasonable. 2. The Functional Explanation Historical Materialism There is a claim, by Marx, in the preface of Critique of Political Economy: “The whole process of social life, political life, and mental life is restrained by the productive method of material life. It is not the case that thought determines the existence; in contrast, the existence determines thought. If the force of production had developed at the certain stage, then it would be not compatible with the previous relationships of production or property. At this moment, the given relationships would become the limitation of the productive force and the social revolution comes at this period” [15]. We can refine a proposition that: the productive force determines the productive relationships by Marx’s words. Marx’s economic interpretation for history and the dualistic viewpoint have been challenged by modern thought. 2.1. The Modern Challenge to Marxist Materialism In the modern tendency, there is a challenge to system of knowledge and history. Some proposals held by philosophers are helpful to figure out various dominant factors. As the result of finding the interval features, Anthony Giddens thinks that the reflective usage of knowledge system makes its 44 Li Yong and Zhang Yi: On Cohen’s Critique of Technology and Social Justice certainty undergo the scrutiny and being modified. Karl Popper said, “All of the science are established on the flow of sand”. E P Thompson, following empirical tradition, pays a lot of attention to crux, by designing a “social existence-experience-social idea” interactive mode, in order to eliminate the distinction between social existence and social idea. Therefore, the history could not be regarded as the natural science ruled by universal principle or model. Regarding to David Harvey, temporal objects cause the continuity of history is difficult to be reserved, and his history-geography materialism has opened the space thinking, that means the space contains double senses including ontology and methodology, even the time is inside it, that is to say the space is the “speaker” of our era. The current changes has been described by Milan Kundera, in “The Book of laughter and Forgetting” in a poem tune: “currently, time goes forward harshly, so that the so-called historical event will be forgotten overnight. The sunlight in the morning also fad away with the dew, therefore, it has not been playing the role as the background in stories of narrator, rather a piece of legend in front of common private lives. History is fading away from memories [13].” Does the historical materialism still well-establish under the rush of modern thoughts? Cohen answered yes. The first step is to clarify the concept of historical materialism. In his mind, “the historical materialism” [15] is a positivism theory that related to social structure and power of historical evolution. By means of functional interpretation, he rewrote the story of historical materialism based on “the productive force determines the relationships of production”. The functional interpreted historical materialism is an updated-version of the traditional. 2.2. The Functional Explanation Historical Materialism In functional interpretation, the feature of interpreted item is explained by the explaining item. For example, birds having hollow bone because it is helpful for flying; the shoes factory product shoes in a large scale is the result of that large scale production will produce economic benefit. The functional explanation confer the reason to why the empirical facts in nature and economic life can run continuously. How can it explain how productive force put forward the historical development? This question can be transformed into whether it is consistent with the law of causality? We try to compare it with the Humean causality to work out the question. Let letter E for reason and letter F for result. In accordance with the definition of functional explanation, the reason why E happens is that it will trigger F, i.e. (E→F) → E. Then the question has been converted into whether “→”indicate “implication”? Hume, in “On the Probable Inference: and On the Notion of causality”, proposed that: "the purposes of inferences are comparing and figuring out the constant and variant relationships between two or more facts [12]." The reason why causality could be the basis of inference is that in accordance with it we can find out the former or later objects/events of the current empirical phenomenon. Only if a result acquires proper proof it could become belief, which means the result deriving from causality playing the role of premise. Causality, as a probable inferring method, is contained in logic that pursues certainty. Hume [12]told us that the notion of causality is the source of reason and effect, at the same time, this notion deriving from the constant link of impression-notion: "comparing between ideas produces certainty, whose another source is steady relationship". Overall, Human causality has following features: (1) the objects linked by causality have close spatial and temporal relationships;(2) reason is in front of result temporally;(3)continuity among reasons and corresponding results. The latest character unfolds in time, basing on experience that beyond our perception, which also implies that if something could be experienced, it will have opportunity to become impression planting into mind. Then we inlet the time variable t into the above formula can get following result: (∀x)(E(x, t1) →(y)F(y, t2)) →((z)E(z, t3)). As it illustrates that time variable t1, t2 and t3 are not in the fixed order, which covers the second character of Humean causality; simultaneously, the continuity of history could be found in historical materialism as well; then the close relationships among individual constants spatially in the functional explanation reflects the first feature. Above all, we could, in a general meaning, acknowledge functional explanation is consistent with Humean causality. Although Hume goes from notion of causality to scepticism ultimately, when the black-box of induction has not been unblocked, the fruitful achievements from natural science defend its rationality. From chart 1, the functional explanation is consistent with empiricalism Table 1. The value of functional explanation. E F E→F (E→F) →F 1 1 1 1 1 2 1 0 0 1 3 0 1 1 0 4 0 0 1 0 Because conditions in the third and fourth rows together, as the last column value of truth is false, these possibilities will be eliminated; then in terms of the first and second rows, if E are true, no matter whether F are true or false, the result will be true. We need to avoid a possible misunderstanding that the value of truth in functional explanation have not be affected by the later items, because causal results would derive from any assumption, which cause the fact that it become the invalid reasoning. Only the inference in the first row that both E and F have true value reflects the empirical facts. Iterating the formula of functional explanation, we can acquire the following results: (1) (E→F) →F (2) ((E→F) →F) → (E→F) (3) (((E→F) →F) → (E→F))→ (E→F) →F) Advances in Sciences and Humanities 2019; 5(2): 43-48 45 The constant and temporal variable have been omitted from formulas. When a simplified functional explanation has been well established, it could be wholly as an antecedent in the next step, at the same time, the antecedent in the original formula would play the role of consequent in new proposition. This process could be repeated and it will always produce true sentences. To interpret empirical objects by this method, constants and temporal variable should be taken into consideration and this practice will be true in the meaning of truth-functions, since in functional explanation is of speciality, antecedent is a proposition, and the inference process starting with the accepted item, so that it is a self-sufficient circulation. Two concepts of “production” and “relationships of production” are introduced into functional explanation. That is “the relationships of production are R category relationships at t, as the result of it is suit for the current productive force, in other words, the level of productive force at t”, which means the productive force only determines the essence of relationships of production rather its whole features [14]. In comparison with the content written by Marx, it is clear this usage of productive force has been captured by historical materialism. 3. Understanding Just in the Technology Perspective G. A. Cohen draws a conclusion that "the essence of the priority of productive force is interpreting relationships of production by virtue of functional explanation [13]" from historical materialism. There is a distinction should be pay attention to is that Marx’s concept of productive force is not same as the productive power. The productive force means a capacity to commit oneself into material production, in which labours playing a role of subject in production, who devote themselves into the sensible and objective activity. In the process of production, the applied technology belongs to productive force, apart from labours. In evaluation of the relationships of production, it is essential to consider the current scientific level. During the high-level of science development period, production should be combined with science, which means "whether an item is or is not productive force is not contingent on its entity, while related to whether it can promote efficiency of production [13]". In the Marxist meaning, the relationship is not ownership in law rather practical dominance, which can control productive matters effectively. When Marx confers the right of determination to productive force, it seems that there are other elements playing important role in the development of society, such as technology, which is regarded as ontology in empiricalism tradition. As the result of overcoming alienation of technology is premise of eliminating technology ontology, Cohen start with it. He analyses historical materialism by “universal” historical materialism and “limited” historical materialism. “In the first category, the development of material and economy explains the characteristic of spirit evolution. In another category, spirit phenomenon cannot determine material development has been emphasized merely. ”Only at this moment, it uses materialism to interpret spirit phenomenon, otherwise, the barrier of material development would appear [17].” Cohen regards historical materialism as a theory that : (1) during the whole process of time, the productive force shows a rising inclination;(2) waves of social forms are due to whether they could serve to the above development. In the viewpoint of Cohen, there are two kinds of historical materialism:(1) the first is systematical development rotating around human productive force;(2)another kind is also systematical development, in which human productive force playing a special role. The “systematisms” of productive development emphases its automatic inclination, which means technology can go ahead by itself to some extent. Technology, out of human control, controls human beings. The autonomy of technology has some following suggestions: firstly, as the force in historical process, technology determines the direction of ideology, so that it becoming criteria in social critique. Secondly, technology is one part inside historical system endowing the interacting to determine the trend in evolution. Then the limitation of interacting between material and spirit is that it is not the case that spirit determines material. Technology alienation also can be eliminated. By functional explanation, Cohen gives the proof for the limited historical materialism proposition, in which “premise” means “adapt” is one-direction action: “if x adapt to y, then y do not need to adapt to x[14].” The systematic development of productive force plays the preliminary role in all elements, under this condition, as the result of one-direction adaption and productive force has been blocked to go backwards, the historical process showing evolutionary feature. In this meaning, Cohen verifies the premise proposition that “there is a certain inclination of productive force throughout history.” Both the nature of kindness and the capacity of rational choice give opportunity to people for modifying their habitats to adapt to life. Iin spite of science has serving effects on human life; it also causes a series problems. The capitalism society, depending on science, possesses substantial material products and vast social capital with large gap of wealth among different people; in the market without management, the property has double implications:(1)the economic ability and power structure based on capital; (2)new power structure causes material productive elements are distributed unequally, thus some people who do not have necessary elements or who only hold partial material resources have no choice but to devote themselves into reluctant work. Cohen started to rethink historical materialism from the viewpoint of philosophical anthropology: as the core of history development, human beings are both energy and narrator of history. Marx has emphasized people are at the centre of productive force, implying dimension of function. Cohen, however, notices human life relies on their own communities, which are defined by race, nationality, and religions apart from economic elements, so that the reason why communities can exist is because they meet the self-identity 46 Li Yong and Zhang Yi: On Cohen’s Critique of Technology and Social Justice of people. The spirit of community directs market into the right path. Because so-called free market does not have freedom in fact, which means if we hope to pursuit freedom and just in current conditions, we will not only need to develop technology, but also to carry out social critique. 4. The Social Critique of Just The aim of social critique is to compromise Marxism with formal philosophy for unifying freedom, equality and just in society. Historical materialism reveal the crux in history, while laws and essence explored by formal philosophy, as its metaphysics principles, are of universal and inevitable assumption. Cohen’s work looks like establishing a formal system, in which the just principle is constant. System designing and moral construction as variables are embedded into it through following process: (1) just principle reflects in practical situations; (2) and inlet empirical events into principles to acquire appropriate realizing scheme. 4.1. Compatibility Between Freedom and Equality Equality and freedom are the common pursuit of human beings, however, whether the glorious ideals could be achieved basing on current social conditions rather than in remote future? It is essential to bear in mind that current capitalism society has strong self-modifying capacity, which has eliminated the revolutionary possibility among the public. Economic crisis makes people loose adequate certainty to assure that by developing technical can create infinite surplus value. As practical situation has been different from Marxist assumption, so that Cohen acknowledge we could realize socialism just ideal by means of system designing and moral education. We hope in the just society, individuals are able to devote themselves into works with own will and individual growth can construct the condition for others free development. Cohen intend to find out a reasonable distribution scheme, which can promote productive development and compromise freedom with equality. He adapts a strategy by modifying theory of Robert Nozick. Nozick supposes just is adequate condition for freedom, because just society deriving from original freedom. However, practical illiberality and unequal phenomenon are result of natural development, so that we should hold tolerant attitude towards it. In spite of Nozick defend for illiberality and inequality; differences in talent and family background have not determined unequal results. Starting from this point, Cohen acknowledges that we have obligation to construct equal philosophy of politics in the relative poor era. In a more specific meaning, we could establish communities to break the limitations endowed by individual families, then people with same ability can acquire equal chance to pursuit their own sufficient development conditions. This also makes requirements for people that they should give up the motivation of “adaptive preference” just and insist principles of communities, serving for each other’s needs. Nozick believes that freedom and equality are contrary to each other. He defends for inequality from two premise:(1) “self-ownership”; (2) nobody can own the natural outer world to themselves. Everyone, who own themselves, devote their labor into outer world, so that the products containing labour of people [15]. Nozick puts forward the condition of if anyone intend to occupy the object O, which has no owner and can be possessed by every people is that the object O exits from public field but it does not make prospect of other people to be worse. While Locke proposed, conditions of ownership includes:(1)individuals can occupy the products that containing their work;(2) they have to leave enough good things for other people;(3) at the same time they have not wasted what they acquired. Above all, Nozick weakens “Locke’s conditions”, because he did not emphasis the first and the third conditions. As the result of Nozick ignored several anti-facts situations, the inequality is not the inevitable outcome deriving from “self-ownership” [10]. Liberals and socialists issue two criteria for freedom and just. Regarding to liberals, who starting from original equality, reconcile it is acceptable that a bit of inequality existing in resources distribution. On the other hand, Cohen designs a new strategy that to construct rational system basing on empirical changes to maintain dynamic equality. In order to realize the scheme, he has designed Able and Infirm model to interpret that the compatibility between union ownership and self-ownership. Society is constituted by the Able and the Infirm in accordance with their productive capacity. The vote is held by the Infirm, which means whatever Able want to product must achieve agreement from the counterpart. At the same time, it is essential to check the Infirm group to rule out the possibility some Able hide in it, so social production efficiency can reach the adequate level. The vitality of co-ownership lies in the consensus of goodness. In a society the Infirm and the Able can convert to each other at different time, in other words, the current Infirm may convert to the Able some years later, vice verse. In spite of there is still competition in the communities, every competitor will not be abandoned as the result of failure in the competition. Liberals, however, hold the point that if union ownership mix with self-ownership, then the later will be eliminated. Assuming the union self-ownership is C(x) and ownership is S(x), formal ownership is F(x) and practical ownership is P(x), veto power is D(x), doing nothing is N(x). Then the point of Nozick can be presented as following: C(A, I) ∧S(A, I) →F(S(A)) C(A, I)∧S(A, I) F(S(A)) Nozick points that if union ownership and self-ownership are contrary to each other, in addition to union ownership is dominant, then self-ownership has been denied.. While Cohen hold different viewpoint that self-ownership is compatible with union ownership, in other words, practical self-ownership does not exclude vote power(P(S(A, I)) ∧D(I)). 1. D(I) ∧F(S(A)) →N(A) ¬N(A) ¬(D(I) ∧F(S(A))) Advances in Sciences and Humanities 2019; 5(2): 43-48 47 2. ¬(D(I) ∧F(S(A)))↔¬D(I) ∨¬F(S(A)) 3. C(A, I)→D(I) C(A, I) D(I) 4. D(I)∧(¬D(I) ∨¬F(S(A))) (D(I)∧¬D(I))∨(D(I)∧¬F(S(A))) D(I)∧¬F(S(A)) ¬F(S(A)) The ultimate result represent that P(S(A, I)) [15] is well-established. When we demonstrate two ownership system can be harmony with each other, the liberty can co-exist with equality in a possible world. 4.2. System Designing of Justice and Equality Rawls hopes to seek out a universal meaning of justice with internalist implicature. It is able to maintain fixed cooperation, because individuals may be on guard for their own interest against others in absolutely situation. The contract is conducted behind the veil of ignorance, that can products just system by means of rational allocation of rights and obligation. When the conflicts of interests happen, it can still keep the society in balance. In the process of allocation, the “the Difference Principle”, the unequal distribution in economy field is of permissibility only if it maximizes the benefits of the least favored [13]. Cohen, however, [2] thinks the so-called “the Difference Principle” is in defense of inequality in nature. Rawls designs just social system in accordance with the spirit basing on “veil of ignorance”. This kind of constructivism justice substitutes “what is justice” with “how to formulate ideal social management rule”. As limited by practical environment, the public have sway away from pure justice and this change causing injustice. Apart from it material stimulation strategy have meet the requirement of “the Difference Principle”: the Able devote themselves into social progress and they should be paid corresponding salaries. Because the whole development of society will be benefit for modify living situation for the poor. On the other hand, as the result of struggling for life, the poor must endure tough life causing by the gap of wealth, thus the stimulating mechanism in “the Difference Principle” compromise with selfish character shaped by capitalism calmly. It is vital that modifying only represents increments, in other words, the weaker still have to rely on the wealthy people for living, and the original inequality will increase in an exponent way as time goes by. In terms of Cohen’s view, the equality between the poor and the wealthy is still a remote ideal under “the Difference Principle”, so that the socialism opportunity equality could be a reasonable alternative, because it merely contains difference in intended choices, which means the inequality caused by variety of choices and preferences. In “why not socialism” Cohen constructs camping trip model to check reciprocal and sharing principle. During the trip everyone has opportunity to go through glorious time with each other by sharing private goods, serving for others with unique talent, and cooperating in accordance with their willing, so that they can become reciprocal friends without worries about struggling for living. The reason why camping trip is glorious locates in equality, the more specific expression is socialism opportunity equality and sharing can realize in it. In order to realize equality we have to wipe away the chance barriers undertaken by the partial. There are also two kinds of chance equality. The first is capitalist chance equality that enlarges the public opportunity by eliminating limitation caused by social idea from right allocation and prejudice [2]. Another is liberalism equality, rejecting inequality deriving from family background, claim to gift and free choice determine individual destiny. While socialism opportunity equality avoids inequality from different talents as well as negative result caused by inevitable conditions. Difference can only reflect interests and choices. In the camping trip people accept inequality in a limited field. Then when we enlarge it to the market, the inequality also increase correspondingly. As it said that “market is inevitable” [2]. Socialism opportunity equal should be improved by sharing principle, that people take care of their companions in the context of market. The purpose and the aim has be tied together, in which “wiling “is the motivation of all actions, thus the inner motivation rooted in the good nature. Cohen hopes to figure out the crux from selfishness and limited technology in the category of socialism equality. Eventually, he attributed the problem to the ignorance of how to use and develop general character to run the market. There is an eclectic method that “inlet strong sharing and equal spirit into selfish choice, at the same time the latest element must be controlled [2]”. This is market socialism. By means of critique theory of Nozick and Rawls, Cohen demonstrates that the equality compatible with freedom and justice respectively. Therefore, just society implies equality, freedom as well as justice, which has been a well-established premise. Cohen’s inspiration enriches the meaning of just. During the process of realizing just ideal, we should not only put forward science and technology reaching higher stage, but also convert the motivation of public, planting individual will into mutual service. The journey to just starts with virtuous kindness from heart. References [1] Cohen, G., 1994. Back to Socialist Basics. New Left Review, 0(207), pp. 3-16. [2] Cohen, G., 2011. Why not Socialism?. Beijing: Renmin press. [3] Cohen, G. A., 1966. Beliefs and Roles. London, Oxford University Press. [4] G. A. Cohen, 1989. On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice. Ethics, 99(4), pp. 906-944. [5] G. A. Cohen, 1995. The Pareto Argument for Inequality. Social Philosophy and Policy Foundation, 12(1), pp. 160-185. [6] G. A. Cohen, 1997. Where the Action is: On the Site of Distributive Justice. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 26(1), pp. 3-30. [7] G. A. Cohen, 2000. If You're an Egalitarian, How Come You're 48 Li Yong and Zhang Yi: On Cohen’s Critique of Technology and Social Justice so Rich?. The Journal of Ethics, 4(1/2), pp. 1-26. [8] G. A. Cohen, 2003. Facts and Principles. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 31(3), pp. 211-245. [9] G. A. Cohen, 2006. Review: Luck and Equality: A Reply to Hurley. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 72(2), pp. 439-446. [10] G. A. Cohen, 2008. Self-ownership, Freedom and Equality. Beijing: Oriental press. [11] Gerald A. Cohen and H. B. Acton, 1970. Symposium: On Some Criticism of Historical Materialism. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 44, pp. 121-156. [12] Hume, D., 2009. A Treatise of Human Nature. Beijing: the commercial press. [13] Qiao Ruijin, et al., 2013. The British Neo-Marxism. Beijing: Renmin press. [14] Wei, C., 2008. On Cohen's ' primary life problem'. Lanzhou Academic Journal, 4(175). [15] Zhongqiao, D., 2013. A Criticism of Libertarianism from the Socialist Perspective: G. A. Cohen's Rebute of Robert [16] Nozick's ' self-ownership' proposition. Social Sciences in China, Issue 11. [17] Zhongqiao, D., 2013. G. A. Cohen's Reconsideration of Historical Materialism. Philosophical Researches, Issue 2, pp. 21-28. [18] Zhongqiao, D., 2013. G. A. Cohen's defense of Three Basic Problems in Historical Materialism. Hebei Academic Journal, 33(2), pp. 29-34. work_5xua5dphavf75aw2vhiltmr3w4 ---- Democratic Distributive Justice Ross Zucker Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2001 ISBN 0-521-7903-36. Contemporary Political Theory (2002) 1, 245–246. DOI: 10.1057/palgrave.cpt.9300033 A curious feature of Anglo-American political theory in recent decades has been the divide between democratic theory and liberal political philosophy. Comparing and contrasting classics of each, notably Dahl’s Democracy and its Critics on one side and Rawls’s A Theory of Justice and Political Liberalism on the other, reveals the democratic theorist’s suspicion of regarding substantive social and economic rights as primary democratic rights, and the theorist of justice’s suspicion of the capacity of merely procedural democracy of the broadly polyarchal (or perhaps ‘aggregative’) kind to produce just outcomes. In Democratic Distributive Justice, Ross Zucker argues in impressive and often meticulous detail for the view that ‘a political system does not qualify as a democracy unless it brings about a just economic order as well’ (p. 277). In this way, he argues that procedural conceptions of democracy F which he sees as dominant in democratic theory, as exemplified by Dahl’s major work F are inadequate, since they fail to recognize and therefore to embrace the importance of a certain form of income equality between citizens. Zucker deduces this substantive economic democratic right by a complex process of reasoning. The essence of the argument is that, in a capitalist economy, wealth is a product of orientations and preferences of consumers as well as producers. All members of the economic system make a contribution to the creation of economic value, since ‘Produced commodities will not have value F will not form particles of wealth F unless they are wanted or needed’ (p. 85). This contribution needs to be recognized, as commonly it is not. The form that such recognition should take, according to Zucker, is a collective commitment to the equalization of a portion of income: ‘since individuals make some equal indirect contributions to value, they are due proportionate benefits’ (p. 280). Much of the book buttresses the varied elements of this deductive argument. Key sections and chapters address liberal theories of property, the ethics of community as they should be applied to the economy, the nature and implications of the endogenous formation of market preferences, and the current state of democratic theory with regard to economic justice. Many parts of the argument are compelling, such as the critique of the liberal ‘hidden premise of subjective personality’ and Contemporary Political Theory, 2002, 1, (245–246) r 2002 Palgrave Macmillan Ltd 1470-8914/02 $15.00 www.palgrave-journals.com/cpt the dependence of capitalist economies on a sub-structure of economic community. The book is erudite, closely reasoned and tightly written, and its tone engaged and serious. Importantly, Zucker gets to the nub of key issues involved in the democratic theory debates he wishes to influence. He sets out with commendable clarity, for example, his view that ‘current ‘‘democracies’’ that lack the redistributory property right do not qualify as true democracies along this dimension’ (p. 6). There are many arguable points, starting with the promotion of unambiguous end-state reasoning at a time when even Rawlsian theorizing has adopted a brand of deliberative proceduralism (whether hypothetical or actual), in the face of criticism of the idea that the reasoned deduction of democratic rights may be a sufficient basis for their acceptance. However, Zucker’s thesis deserves widespread attention both for its tight and comprehensive character and for its substantive importance at a time of widening inequalities in market economies. Michael Saward Faculty of Social Sciences, The Open University. Book Reviews 246 Contemporary Political Theory 2002 1 Democratic Distributive Justice work_5zq7k5onwrg4pifdmnaouzzxsa ---- 12Chapt6Kiernan.p65 92 Human Rights Review, April-June 2000 92 Bringing the Khmer Rouge to Justice Ben Kiernan In 1974, I began a quarter century of research on the Khmer Rouge move- ment. As an undergraduate I wrote an empirical study of their insurgency against the Sihanouk regime in the late 1960s1 and soon published several shorter articles. At first I was relatively sympathetic to their purported reforms and nationalism, but when I commenced Ph.D. research in 1978, I acknowl- edged my error and began a two-decade project of documenting the crimes of the Khmer Rouge regime.2 By 1980 I had interviewed hundreds of Cambo- dian survivors and had begun to publish their accounts.3 In Australia during the 1980s, I translated most of my interviews, as well as key Khmer Rouge documents, and wrote detailed accounts of specific aspects of the genocide.4 I also published historical analyses of the Khmer Rouge rise to power.5 At Yale University in 1994, I established the Cambodian Genocide Program, to continue this work with a grant from the U.S. Department of State. In Janu- ary 1995, we opened the Documentation Center of Cambodia in Phnom Penh. Four years later, the United Nations Group of Experts completed its report to UN Secretary-General Kofi Annan on the legal ramifications of the Cambo- dian Genocide. In March 1999, this report was published by the Secretary- General. It stated: Over the last 20 years, various attempts have been made to gather evidence of Khmer Rouge atrocities to build a historical record of these acts. For nearly 20 years, scholars have been accumulating such evidence by talking with survivors and par- ticipants in the terror and reviewing documents, photographs, and gravesites. The most impressive and organized effort in this regard is the Documentation Center of Cambodia, located in Phnom Penh. Originally set up by Yale University through a grant from the Government of the United States of America, the Center now func- tions as an independent research institute with funding from several governments and foundations. It has conducted a documentation project to collect, catalogue and store documents of Democratic Kampuchea, as well as a mapping project to locate sites of execution centres and mass graves.6 The report went on to recommend the creation of an international tribunal to judge the crimes of the Khmer Rouge leadership. Cambodia is now study- ing the establishment of a “mixed” national and international tribunal. This Kiernan 93 success was achieved under fire, not only from the Khmer Rouge, but also a sustained barrage from the West’s most powerful newspaper. The Cambodian Genocide Program, 1994–1999 “The only research operation in the world that focuses on Khmer Rouge atrocities, apart from Yale’s genocide program.” This is how the Editor-at-Large of the the Asian Wall Street Journal described the Documentation Center of Cambodia in 1997.7 Despite this, the Wall Street Journal led a campaign against Yale’s Cambodian Genocide Program (CGP) throughout the two-year period in which the CGP created the Documentation Center.8 April 17, 1995, marked the twentieth anniversary of the seizure of power by the genocidal Khmer Rouge regime. The Wall Street Journal chose the occasion for a long editorial-page article appealing to the U.S. State Department and Congress to revoke the Department’s inaugurating grant to the CGP, labeling its Director (me) a “communist” with Khmer Rouge sympathies. The appeal failed after the Journal published responses, but the paper followed with further ad hom- inem barrages, again directed at the CGP’s source of funds. Fortunately, this pro- voked an encouraging display of support, including letters from twenty-nine leading international Cambodia specialists and various other scholars in my defense.9 The Khmer Rouge, meanwhile, “indicted” me as an “arch-war criminal” and an “ac- cessory executioner of the U.S. imperialists.”10 Despite attacks from two sides, we pursued our mandate to establish a comprehensive, publicly accessible archive and documentation database on the Khmer Rouge genocide, and to train Cambodian scholars and archivists to manage and enhance it. The next year, the Asian Wall Street Journal fired another volley at the CGP, this time chastising us for not giving priority to the search for U.S. servicemen missing in action from the 1970-75 Cambodian war—before the Khmer Rouge takeover.11 To discourage further funding for the CGP, the article described me as “the grant world’s equivalent of box office poison.” The Wall Street Jour- nal republished this piece and proclaimed to readers in an accompanying edi- torial that the CGP was closing down the next month.12 None of this was true—though the Journal now declined to print responses or corrections.13 In that three-month period, the CGP in fact raised $1.5 million, quadrupling its original grant. The CGP and the Documentation Center of Cambodia were now assured of funding for the next five years, a prospect beyond our wildest hopes in 1995. The Documentation Center, with the massive archive of Khmer Rouge internal documents we assembled in 1995-96, has now become Cambodia’s first independent research institute on the history of Pol Pot’s Khmer Rouge regime, known as “Democratic Kampuchea” (DK), which pre- sided over the deaths of 1.7 million people. Why did the Wall Street Journal launch such a campaign in 1995? Why the attempt to scuttle the world’s only research operation on the Cambodian geno- 94 Human Rights Review, April-June 2000 cide? Why did the Journal choose the same target as the Khmer Rouge did? Why did it fail? What is the nexus between denial of genocide and attempts to foreclose its investigation? In this case, as we shall see, there is a complex relationship between assertion and suppression.14 I will discuss two forms of denial of the Cambodian genocide and one of suppression. First, the outright attempt to deny that anything serious oc- curred. In 1984, Bunroeun Thach, then of the University of Syracuse’s po- litical science department, took this position. He praised “Democratic Kampuchea political leaders” for having successfully “buried the past,” at- tacked what he called Hanoi’s campaign “to discredit the Communist Party of Kampuchea,” and argued for including the Khmer Rouge in Cambodia’s future.15 Thach won few scholarly converts, but another Cambodian with similar views was Sorpong Peou, who opposed legal accountability for the Khmer Rouge geno- cide. As late as March 1997, Peou proclaimed: “Punishing Pol Pot will not solve the problem.” He added: “Prosecution in a condition of anarchy is wishful thinking and may hinder national reconciliation.” The journalist who interviewed him re- ported that Peou “says he is willing to forgive for the sake of breaking the cycle of deception and pre-emptive violence.” The reporter also wrote: “Sorpong supports reconciliation with the Khmer Rouge rather than punishment for past crimes [and] supports the pragmatic strategy of incorporating Khmer Rouge defectors into the government structure in the hope that the movement will die a natural death.”16 Peou’s apologetics for the Khmer Rouge was more influential than Bunroeun Thach’s. Holocaust and Genocide Studies published his review of my 1996 book The Pol Pot Regime. In his review, Poeu called the Khmer Rouge leaders “so- called ‘genocidists.’” He linked what he called “the pre-emptive nature of the violence” to “Pol Pot’s egalitarianism,” his “prudence,” “insecurity,” and “vulnerability,” and “the fickleness of popular support.”17 Extraordinarily, Peou claimed, “From 1970 to 1975, the Cham Muslims were not perse- cuted at all.” When he did acknowledge massacres of Chams, he denied they were premeditated, despite overwhelming evidence. He then claimed that “the Pol Pot group made several—unsuccessful—attempts to limit the killing.”18 It is extraordinary to read such assertions in the journal of the U.S. Holocaust Memorial Museum. Few authors have shown such boldness in defending the Khmer Rouge genocidists. A colleague of Peou’s, Stephen R. Heder, in 1991, described most of the top-level Khmer Rouge leaders as “dissidents” who were “suspect in the eyes of Pol Pot.” These alleged “dissidents” even included Son Sen, Deputy Prime Minister and CPK Security chief, Chhit Choeun alias Ta Mok, the Khmer Rouge military commander, Ke Pauk, the deputy military com- mander, and Deuch, the chief of the notorious Tuol Sleng prison. Heder wrote that “such surviving dissidents as Son Sen and Kae Pok and perhaps even Ta Mok and Deuch have been wrongly depicted as ‘Pol Pot loyalists.’” Kiernan 95 Heder went on to assert that “there were only two prominent Kampuchean communists who were not suspect in the eyes of Pol Pot and Nuon Chea. They were Ieng Sary...and Khiev Samphan....Both Ieng Sary and Khiev Samphan were apparently considered completely loyal and lacking the domestic political strength with which to challenge Pol Pot and Nuon Chea in any way.”19 However, when Ieng Sary and Khieu Samphan came within reach of legal action, Heder backpedalled. In 1996, Ieng Sary defected to the Cambodian government. Heder now described Ieng Sary as having shown signs of “dis- sent and deviation” from Pol Pot’s policies. In Ieng Sary’s zone in the 1980s, “it was possible for peasants to accumulate small amounts of wealth,” Heder said, adding that “China would have seen Ieng Sary as more reasonable” than Pol Pot. Moreover, Heder reportedly went on, “those differences may have existed” under the Pol Pot regime from 1975 to 1979, “with Ieng Sary advocating a more tolerant attitude toward intellectuals and being accused in the Communist inner circle of wanting to coddle the bourgeois elite.” Heder added, “There’s no evidence to suggest that Ieng Sary was ever No. 2, or that he had the kind of power base to allow him to enforce his will.”20 (Sary was in fact No. 3 to Pol Pot. Hypocritically, Heder branded the Cambodian Genocide Program as soft on Sary!)21 A Khmer Rouge aide to Ieng Sary even quoted Heder’s statements on Radio France-Internationale that, “according to the documents I have re- ferred to, Mr. Ieng Sary is the only one, among Khmer Rouge leaders, about whom I have so far been unable to gather tangible evidence showing that he initiated or applied purges against intellectuals.”22 Khieu Samphan was certainly not in that category. In another 1991 paper, Heder had concluded: “Khieu Samphan’s political star rose literally on heaps of corpses. He continued to rise in importance as he helped Pol Pot purge other communists….” Samphan, according to Heder, was “one of the key ac- complices in the political execution machine that Pol Pot created” and “one of Pol Pot’s chief servitors, second perhaps only to Nuon Chea.”23 But again, in 1999, after Khieu Samphan surrendered with Nuon Chea, Heder suddenly began to state that the case against Samphan was inadequate: “There are cases to be answered by Khieu Samphan and Ieng Sary, but on the avail- able documentary evidence you have to be less confident they would ever be convicted....There is other evidence against Khieu Samphan that implicates him in the purge process but little or no documentary evidence that would stand up in court. But that’s not to say we won’t suddenly dig up such a docu- ment tomorrow.” Indeed, Heder has now dug up evidence to convict those he had described in 1991 as anti-Pol Pot “dissidents.” Mok and Ke Pauk, as well as Nuon Chea, could be indicted on the basis of transcripts of messages between these cen- tral leaders and zone commanders relating to arrests and killings. But in an interview with a reporter, “Heder said the weakness of the cases against Khieu 96 Human Rights Review, April-June 2000 Samphan and Ieng Sary related to ‘indirect command responsibility,’ a con- tentious issue under international law.” 24 This is false. War crimes cases do require proof of “command responsibility,” but in cases of crimes against humanity and genocide, what is needed is proof of a conspiracy. International lawyer Dr. Gregory Stanton writes: Heder is wrong about Khieu Samphan and Ieng Sary’s culpability for crimes against humanity and genocide. All one needs to show for those crimes is participation in a conspiracy. To prove their attendance at meetings of the Central Committee where decisions were made to eradicate Chams or to uproot everybody in the Eastern Zone would be enough. Ieng Sary’s diary evidently shows that he was well aware of the plans to exterminate the enemies of the party. Khieu Samphan can probably be shown to have been equally aware of the party’s policies.25 He was. We have complete copies of the minutes of fifteen meetings of the most powerful body in Democratic Kampuchea—the Standing Committee of the Central Committee of the ruling Communist Party of Kampuchea. These crucial Standing Committee meetings were held between October 9, 1975 and May 30, 1976. Khieu Samphan is recorded in the minutes (under his revolu- tionary name Hem) as having attended twelve of these fifteen meetings. The minutes of two of the meetings do not record who was present, but it is likely that Samphan was there as well, totaling fourteen out of the fifteen meetings for which we have evidence. At the meeting of October 9, 1975, the Standing Committee put Samphan “in charge of the Front and the Royal Government; [and of] the accountancy and pricing aspects of commerce.” Samphan was also made President of the State Presidium (i.e., Head of State of Democratic Kampuchea) by a decision of the Central Committee on March 30, 1976.26 In 1977-78, he also headed the powerful Office of the CPK Central Committee (“Office 870”). In April 1977, soon after he assumed this post, Samphan de- clared publicly, “We must wipe out the enemy [and] suppress all stripes of enemy at all times.”27 The diary of an aide to Ieng Sary reveals the following view: “In our country, one percent to five percent are traitors, boring in....[T]he enemies are on our body, among the military, the workers, in the cooperatives and even in our ranks....These enemies must be progressively wiped out.”28 More common than Heder’s mental gymnastics is a consistent view that what occurred under the Khmer Rouge, though murderous, was not genocide. Two historians of Cambodia, Michael Vickery of the University Sains Malaysia and Monash University’s David P. Chandler, both take this position. They op- pose the Khmer Rouge, but they have categorized the regime’s crimes as other than genocidal.29 Vickery, who considers the Khmer Rouge guilty of “intolerable violence” and “mass murder,” argues that in Cambodia, unlike China and Vietnam, “na- tionalism, populism and peasantism really won out over communism.”30 “The violence of DK was first of all because it was such a complete peasant revolu- tion, with the victorious peasant revolutionaries doing what peasant rebels Kiernan 97 have always wanted to do to their urban enemies.”31 Vickery believes an or- thodox Marxist regime would have been preferable. Chandler, by contrast, holds Marxism responsible for the violence, downplaying other factors like racist or genocidal policies. He argues, “Under the regime of Democratic Kampuchea (DK), a million Cambodians, or one in eight, died from warfare, starvation, overwork, misdiagnosed diseases, and executions. Most of these deaths, how- ever, were never intended by DK. Instead, one Cambodian in eight fell victim to the government’s utopian program of total and rapid social transformation, which its leaders had expected would succeed at far less cost.”32 This technical denial of genocide, though in my view incorrect, is quite le- gitimate.33 Vickery and Chandler do not fit into the category of Holocaust revisionists like Serge Thion, who deny the very concept and the plausibility of genocide. Thion indefensibly prefers the term “deportation” for the fate of Jews in Nazi-occupied Europe, and casts doubt on the evidence for the gas cham- bers.34 (In the Cambodian case, Thion argues that the Khmer Rouge’s crimes should be tried in a Cambodian court, rather than an international one.)35 By contrast, arguments that the Cambodian people suffered not genocide but “a peasantist revolution of the purest sort” (Vickery) or “the purest and most thoroughgoing Marxist-Leninist revolution” (Chandler),36 have a defensible intellectual basis. The analyses of Vickery and Chandler are also more honest than a third position which consists, in the style of the Wall Street Journal editorial page, in noting that genocide occurred, while attempting to block investigation of it. I shall now examine various attempts to suppress the CGP’s historical account- ing of the Cambodian genocide, in the hope of uncovering a lesson for future chroniclers of crimes against humanity. In conclusion, I shall weigh the argu- ments of those who reject use of the term “genocide” in the Cambodian case, against the actions of those who have tried either to turn public inquiry to other issues, or simply to suppress the facts of the case. The first attempt to derail the CGP came from a man describing himself as “a poor Chilean, a citizen of the Third World.”37 Julio A. Jeldres had left Chile before the 1973 coup, and subsequently moved to Australia and then Cambo- dia. In the 1970s, Jeldres not only was a supporter of the Pinochet military dictatorship in Chile, but was also a member of a Khmer Rouge international front organization.38 Within weeks of our launching the Cambodian Geno- cide Program, in 1995 Jeldres published an article entitled “Genocide Investi- gation Off on the Wrong Foot.”39 In reply, I noted Jeldres’ support for the Pinochet regime.40 Jeldres quickly denied “doing work for the regime” of General Pinochet, claiming he was “a member of the Chilean Folk Dance Group, a non-political, cultural associa- tion.”41 But a statement Jeldres published in 1975, which he signed as “Presi- dent of the Chilean Club,” made no mention of folk dance. In it, Jeldres expressed his sympathies with Pinochet’s Chile, which he called a victim of 98 Human Rights Review, April-June 2000 “the Australian government’s attitude to my country.” He praised Pinochet’s 1973 coup for ensuring merely that “marxism was ousted.” Instead of protest- ing the destruction of Chilean democracy, Jeldres denounced the international outcry over it. Like Pinochet, he equated democracy with communism, and complained that the Chilean dictatorship was “the ‘target’ of a communist international campaign against us.”42 So it was not surprising to find Jeldres later attempting to block action against another murderous regime, this time in Cambodia—especially because for at least five years, he had been an “Honorary Member” of the Khmer Rouge front organization known as FUNK. In 1976, he had privately boasted of this con- tinued “honorary” status.43 In 1978, at the height of the genocide, Jeldres sided with the Khmer Rouge against their Vietnamese opponents, and even claimed that the Pol Pot regime told him all he needed to know. As he then put it, “I am kept fully informed by the Cambodian Embassy in Peking.”44 In 1995, cam- paigning against the CGP’s investigation of the Khmer Rouge period, Jeldres continued to claim that in 1978, Pol Pot’s embassy “was the only source of information on what was going on in Cambodia.”45 He was alone in exclud- ing consideration of information from refugees and victims of the genocide. In the 1980s, Jeldres was associated with another Khmer Rouge front, the exiled Coalition Government of Democratic Kampuchea.46 In the early 1990s, he joined the magazine Khmer Conscience, which published the writings of Bunroeun Thach (see earlier reference).47 In Cambodia’s English-language press in 1995 and 1996, Jeldres continued to denounce the CGP’s investiga- tion of the Khmer Rouge regime.48 Attempts by such people to suppress the only research program to docu- ment Khmer Rouge crimes comprise a new variation on the politics of geno- cide “denial.” Longtime allies and even members of Khmer Rouge organizations have portrayed themselves as opponents of the genocide, thus seeking cred- ibility for their demand that its investigation be cut short. This political chica- nery should not, however, be confused with differing definitions of genocide, or with other scholarly debate about the nature of the tragedy. The Wall Street Journal attack on the CGP was begun by Stephen J. Morris, who had met Julio Jeldres in Bangkok a decade earlier.49 Throughout the 1980s, Morris, like Jeldres and Bunroeun Thach, devoted himself to political activism in support of Cambodian factions who were allied to the communist Khmer Rouge, but whom Morris praised as “anti-communist.” In 1989, Morris com- plained that the democratic government of Thailand was selling out the Khmer Rouge. “It has now gone so far that Thai commanders have provided Phnom Penh’s artillery commanders with precise intelligence on the location of Khmer Rouge units.”50 In the winter of 1990, Morris addressed a meeting of Cambo- dians in Brighton, Massachusetts. According to witnesses, Morris “took the floor and in an impassioned speech warned Cambodians in the room that they should not do anything that would appear to support the Vietnamese Kiernan 99 backed government of Cambodia, including bringing attention to Khmer Rouge atrocities. He did not support a trial of the Khmer Rouge and attributed his inside information about the Cambodian situation to having dined with Khmer Rouge leaders.”51 Morris wrote, “The real Khmer Rouge military aim...is to force Phnom Penh to accept a comprehensive political settlement such as the UN peace plan.”52 His attack on the CGP’s investigation of the Khmer Rouge was predictable. So was Morris’ praise for Stephen Heder, whose “pro-Khmer Rouge views” Morris had once noted.53 More surprising was the Wall Street Journal’s readiness to give space to a writer who had embarrassed it once before. In 1990 Morris attacked Lesley Cockburn, an American Broadcasting Company producer, for her feature on Cambodia.54 Objecting to the feature’s accurate portrayal of the United States’ diplomatic support for the Khmer Rouge in the 1980s, Morris also pilloried what he called “Ms. Cockburn’s 1987 PBS Documentary, ‘Murder on the Rio San Juan.’” Cockburn had had nothing to do with that program, and the Journal’s Editor conceded that Morris had made “an error.”55 The Journal’s assault on the CGP attracted the attention of the Reader’s Di- gest, which investigated reprinting it. A Digest research editor called me on May 22, 1995, to ask, among other things, if I had ever used Marxist terms. He then called the head of my department at Yale and asked if I was a communist. More confidently, he questioned another senior member of the department, “Did you know Kiernan was a communist?” But when my reply to Morris’ second attack appeared in the Wall Street Journal on May 30, the Digest de- cided not to republish his article. The Journal gave Morris a third opportunity to repeat his allegations. The last word came when twenty-nine international Cambodia scholars wrote that “Kiernan has been an outspoken and untiring opponent of the Khmer Rouge for 17 years,” while “Morris supported a coalition government-in-exile which was dominated by the Khmer Rouge.” These scholars, who included Vickery and Chandler, despite their differences with the CGP on the issue of geno- cide, added: “We have full confidence in Professor Kiernan’s integrity, profes- sional scholarship, and ability to carry out the important work of the Cambodian Genocide Program.”56 Thus, a phase of the campaign ended. Having lost the debate in the aca- demic world and the media, Morris moved to the realm of raw power. Ron Marks, a CIA officer seconded as Special Assistant to then Senator Bob Dole, drafted a letter repeating Morris’ charges against me. Six senior Republican Senators—Dole, Senate Majority Leader Trent Lott, Senate Foreign Relations Committee head Jesse Helms, and three others—sent the letter to the U.S. Secretary of State on August 7, 1995. Two of the signatories, Trent Lott and Jesse Helms, were associated with the Council of Conservative Citizens, which claims, among other things, that interracial marriage “amounts to white geno- cide,” that Jews have “turned spite into welfare billions for themselves,” and 100 Human Rights Review, April-June 2000 that African Americans and Latinos suffer from “high crime and low intelli- gence.” In 1992, Senator Trent Lott had given the keynote speech to a national board meeting of the Council. “The people in this room stand for the right principles and the right philosophy,” he said (six years later Lott falsely claimed that he had “no firsthand knowledge” of the Council’s views).57 As the letter went off to Albright, a Morris backer from the conservative Heritage Foundation approached Alphonse LaPorta, head of the State Department’s Office of Cambodian Genocide Investigations, and said, “If you don’t get rid of Kiernan, we’ll go after you.”58 LaPorta concluded that if I did not step down, the Senate would revoke the grant to the CGP, ending our investigation of the Khmer Rouge regime. I held my ground, with strong sup- port from Yale University. On October 2, new support arrived. An editorial in the conservative Washington Times praised the CGP’s achievements and de- scribed the Morris and Dole campaign against me as “lunacy.”59 The issue blew over with the CGP’s Congressional backing enhanced.60 On September 17, 1996, Nancy deWolf Smith of the Asian Wall Street Jour- nal called me from Hong Kong. She said something “is becoming an issue.” This was that the previous month the Pentagon had not gained immediate access to the archives of the Khmer Rouge secret police, which CGP staff from the Documentation Center had discovered in Phnom Penh in March 1996. Smith had the impression, which we could not confirm, that these 1975-79 documents contained information on the fate of Americans missing in Cambodia from the 1970-75 war. I explained that the Pentagon had not consulted me before send- ing its contract researchers directly to Cambodia the previous month. They had arrived at the Documentation Center saying, “It’s all settled.” They wanted to start work then and there, before the files had been catalogued. On September 12, I invited them to return in January, after we had com- pleted our documentation of the Khmer Rouge genocide for the State Depart- ment. The Documentation Center, with CGP funding, would then be free to serve the Pentagon’s different needs. On October 23, James W. Wold of the Pentagon’s MIA office accepted my offer. I responded on October 25, recon- firming to General Wold that his researcher David Chandler was welcome to work in the Documentation Center’s archives in January-February 1997.61 Wold’s office called that afternoon to thank me. The State Department fol- lowed suit, as did Chandler.62 Three days later, on October 29, in the Asian Wall Street Journal, Smith falsely accused me of withholding cooperation from Pentagon researchers.63 I re- plied by fax on November 4, but Smith’s newspaper held back my reply, pass- ing it on to the Wall Street Journal in New York. On December 5, Mr. George Melloan, the Journal’s Deputy Editor (International), requested a copy of “the letter you received from General Wold.”64 I faxed it to Melloan immediately. This letter confirms my September 12 offer to the Pentagon. However, on De- cember 19, the Journal republished Smith’s October piece, alongside an edito- Kiernan 101 rial stating: “Mr. Kiernan refused the Pentagon researchers access to the docu- ments. He continues to do so to this day, and will continue to do so until his project closes.”65 Two weeks earlier, Melloan had received irrefutable evi- dence that we had scheduled the Pentagon’s visit for the following month. This dishonest editorial appeared simultaneously in the Asian Wall Street Journal.66 Both newspapers also finally printed my short letter of Novem- ber 4, but refused to publish corrections to their new editorial. Mr. Terrill E. Lautz, Vice-President of the Henry Luce Foundation, wrote that I had re- ceived a $250,000 grant from his foundation—in October 1996, just as Smith was describing me as “the grant world’s equivalent of box office poison.” The Journal declined to print this letter, Yale’s own reply, or even a letter from the Pentagon. The paper left readers, potential funders, and the Khmer Rouge with the false impression that the CGP was to “close” in January 1997.67 On the contrary, in January 1997 the CGP launched a new World Wide Web site, including four large databases documenting the crimes of the Khmer Rouge regime.68 Chandler worked in the Documentation Center’s archives in Febru- ary 1997 as arranged, and returned in May. Though neither he nor his Penta- gon employers have yet announced whether he has found any information on American MIAs, Chandler again thanked us for our cooperation. We have seen no such acknowledgement from the Wall Street Journal. But the Editor-at-Large of the Asian Wall Street Journal reports our continued existence as “the only research operation in the world that focuses on Khmer Rouge atrocities.” In a turnaround paralleling that in the U.S. Senate, the Readers’ Digest praised the CGP and the Documentation Center: “Even today, project workers are uncov- ering masses of files that point to Pol Pot’s ‘bureaucracy of death.’ Moreover, Yale won a commitment from the Cambodian government to endorse initia- tives that would bring the evidence—and Khmer Rouge leaders—to a crimi- nal trial.”69 Meanwhile, the Khmer Rouge split, with one faction led by Ieng Sary launch- ing its own “Research and Documentation Center” to defend itself.70 In June 1997, the two Cambodian Prime Ministers appealed to the United Nations to establish a tribunal to judge the crimes of the Khmer Rouge period. In early 1998, the UN assembled a group of distinguished legal experts to report on this issue. They visited the Documentation Center of Cambodia in November 1998 and examined the evidence in detail. Their report, delivered to the UN Secretary-General in February 1999, recommended the establishment of an Ad Hoc International Criminal Tribunal to pass judgement on the Khmer Rouge leaders, and a truth commission to be held in Cambodia to allow the surviving victims to air their grievances more fully. Pol Pot died in his sleep in April 1998, less than a year after murdering his former Security chief, Son Sen, whom he suspected of attempting to follow Ieng Sary’s defection to the government. But the 1998 mutiny and defection of 102 Human Rights Review, April-June 2000 former Khmer Rouge deputy commander Ke Pauk and the surrender of Khieu Samphan and Nuon Chea mean that three of the last Khmer Rouge leaders at large are now capable of being apprehended. The lone, one-legged military com- mander Chhit Choeun, alias Mok, did not last long in the jungle. He was captured in March 1999 and sent before a Cambodian military court. Meanwhile, four of the five Permanent Members of the UN Security Council made strong statements in support of the establishment of an international tribunal. In this period, new attempts were made to stymie the work of the Cambo- dian Genocide Program. In May 1998, Congressman Tom Campbell (R-Cali- fornia) wrote another letter to the U.S. Secretary of State, supported by Vietnam veteran and former Reagan appointee John Parsons Wheeler III. This time the allegation was mismanagement of the CGP’s State Department grant. After a six-month inquiry, the Office of Investigations of the U.S. Inspector-General found “no evidence of wrongdoing” and closed its investigation.71 Meanwhile Campbell’s colleague, Congressman Dana Rohrabacher (R-California) and Senator Jesse Helms of North Carolina proposed a resolution (H.Res. 533) that would try Cambodian Prime Minister Hun Sen as a “war criminal”—rather than pursue what Rohrabacher called the “obsession with a handful of geriat- ric Khmer Rouge leaders.”72 When two of the geriatric genocidists, Nuon Chea and Khieu Samphan, surrendered to the Cambodian government and the U.S. Government called for them to be sent before an international tribunal, Stephen Morris made a final attempt to prevent a genocide trial. He wrote a short piece for Commen- tary criticizing the “useless Genocide Warning Center” which the U.S. Gov- ernment had established the previous month. Morris now pronounced that “genocide is extremely rare” and that “the only unambiguous example of genocide to have occurred since the Nazi Holocaust” was the 1994 Rwandan case. In Morris’s view, Cambodians did not suffer a genocide, because “the persecution of ethnic minorities was only a relatively minor aspect of policy” in the Khmer Rouge period.73 Morris’s colleague, Adam Garfinkle, writing in the Los Angeles Times, took up the case against an international tribunal for Cambodia. Firstly, he agreed that “the atrocities of Cambodia repre- sented a nearly pure political and ideological madness, not an ethnic or religious one. For this reason, the application of the term genocide to what happened in Cambodia between 1974 and 1979 is improper.” Secondly, Garfinkle added, “What business is the fate of two aged and defeated kill- ers—Khieu Samphan and Nuon Chea—to the U.S. Government? Did any American perish at the hands of these deranged thugs?” And thirdly, he con- cluded, a tribunal “is liable to dredge up no little amount of embarrassment about the American role in recent Cambodian history....[W]e were indeed there at the creation of Cambodia’s troubles. For purely prudential reasons, then, a U.S. initiative aimed at exhuming our own policy ancestor, so to speak, seems very ill-advised.”74 Kiernan 103 This close look at the failed efforts to impede the task of the CGP enables us to see firsthand how denial and suppression of information about genocide work. Both the creation of historical memory and its erasure depend upon contemporary politics as much as history itself. Bunroeun Thach, Julio Jeldres, Stephen Morris, Congressional Republicans, and the Wall Street Journal edito- rial page all considered their own political agenda more important than docu- menting the crimes of the Khmer Rouge and bringing the criminals to trial for genocide. This agenda reflected the anti-Soviet alliance between the United States and China during the later stages of the Cold War, an alliance which often brought together conservative anti-communists and Maoist radicals. We see such a combination in this case. Priorities for members of this coalition usually included disguising their own past support for the Khmer Rouge, bury- ing the history of the Vietnam War, and yet refighting it by both covering for the Khmer Rouge and fanning the flames of the MIA issue.75 Justice for the victims of the Khmer Rouge was not among their priorities. Those who sought it were often attacked from two sides. Neither Congressional Republicans nor the Wall Street Journal denied that the Cambodian genocide occurred. Rather, they took extraordinary measures to prevent or divert investigation of that genocide. A determined campaign by some of the United States’ most powerful politicians and one of the world’s most powerful newspapers failed. But it posed a larger obstacle to a historical accounting for the genocide than did scholars preferring to use their own con- cepts, or explanations beyond the wording of the Genocide Convention. Most scholars reflexively welcome further research and documentation. By contrast, political pressure is the greatest threat to honest inquiry. And the best defense is a deeper exchange of ideas, further scholarship, and more determination. Pol Pot is dead, and the Khmer Rouge army has collapsed in division and defeat. All surviving Khmer Rouge leaders have surrendered, defected, or been captured. The first trials, of Pol Pot’s military commander, Chhit Choeun (alias Mok), and of the Khmer Rouge Security Chief, Kang Khek Iev (alias Deuch), may begin soon in Phnom Penh. Charges of genocide have also been pre- pared against Nuon Chea and Khieu Samphan. In spite of all of the politics involved in the documentation of events in Cambodia, it appears that getting history right has proceeded hand in hand with the quest for justice. Notes 1. Ben Kiernan, The Samlaut Rebellion and Its Aftermath, 1967-70: The Origins of Cambodia’s Liberation Movement, Parts I and II (Monash University, Centre of Southeast Asian Stud- ies, 1975). 2. Ben Kiernan, “Why’s Kampuchea Gone to Pot?,” Nation Review, November 17, 1978. 3. “Kampuchea: A Refugee’s Account,” Journal of Contemporary Asia 9:3 (1979): 369-74. See also Ben Kiernan, “People Heng in against Pol Pot,” Nation Review, April 5, 1979; “Kampuchea: Thai Neutrality a Farce,” Nation Review, May 24, 1979; “Die Erfahrungen der Frau Hong Var in Kampuchea der Jahre 1975-1979,” Kursbuch 57 (October 1979): 122-129 104 Human Rights Review, April-June 2000 (with Chanthou Boua); “Motsattningarna inom den kommunistiska rorelsen i Kampuchea,” Kommentar 8 (1979): 4-25; “Pol Pots uppgång och fall,” Kommentar 11 (1979): 16-34; “Flyktingintervjuer om mat, arbete, halsa samre 1977-78?” Vietnam Nu 4 (1979): 10-11 (with Chanthou Boua); “Het Verhal Van Hok Sarun: Het level van een arme boer onder Pol Pot,” Vietnam Bulletin 8 (November 15, 1979): 22-24 (with Chanthou Boua); “Background to a Tragedy,” New Straits Times, December 20, 1979; “Why the Slaughter?” Nation Review, January 1980: 40; “Bureaucracy of Death: Documents from Inside Pol Pot’s Torture Ma- chine,” New Statesman, May 2, 1980: 669-676 (with C. Boua and A. Barnett); “Students Killed in Kampuchea,” Sydney Tribune, May 14, 1980. 4. Ben Kiernan, “Genocide in de Oostelijke Zone,” Vietnam Bulletin 16 (June 25, 1980): 20-22; “Wild Chickens, Farm Chickens, and Cormorants: Kampuchea’s Eastern Zone under Pol Pot,” in David Chandler and Ben Kiernan (eds.), Revolution and its Aftermath in Kampuchea (New Haven, CT: Yale University Southeast Asia Council, 1983), 136-211; “Kampuchea and Stalinism,” in Marxism in Asia, ed. C. Mackerras et al. (London: Croom Helm, 1985), 232-250; Cambodia: The Eastern Zone Massacres (Columbia University Center for the Study of Human Rights, 1986); “Kampuchea’s Ethnic Chinese Under Pol Pot,” Journal of Contem- porary Asia 16:1 (1986): 18-29; “Orphans of Genocide: The Cham Muslims of Kampuchea under Pol Pot,” Bulletin of Concerned Asian Scholars 20:4 (1988): 2-33; Chanthou Boua, David Chandler, and Ben Kiernan, eds., Pol Pot Plans the Future: Confidential Leadership Documents from Democratic Kampuchea, 1976-77 (New Haven, CT: Yale Southeast Asia Council, 1988); “The Genocide in Cambodia, 1975-1979,” Bulletin of Concerned Asian Scholars 22:2 (1990): 35-40. 5. Ben Kiernan, “Conflict in the Kampuchean Communist Movement,” Journal of Contempo- rary Asia 10:1-2 (1980): 7-74; Peasants and Politics in Kampuchea, 1942-1981 (London: Zed, 1982) (with Chanthou Boua); How Pol Pot Came To Power: A History of Communism in Kampuchea, 1930-1975 (London: Verso, 1985). 6. United Nations, AS, General Assembly, Security Council, A/53/850, S/1999/231, March 16, 1999, Annex, Report of the Group of Experts for Cambodia established pursuant to General Assembly resolution 52/135, 16. 7. Barry Wain, “Pol Pot’s Paper Trail,” Asian Wall Street Journal, May 9-10, 1997. 8. I refer specifically to the Wall Street Journal editorial page, with its tradition of hamfisted ideological campaigning. See “The Big Lie Theory of the Country’s Biggest Newspaper,” in Extra!, the journal of Fairness and Accuracy in Reporting (FAIR), 8:5 (September/October 1995): 13-24. 9. Stephen J. Morris, “The Wrong Man to Investigate Cambodia,” Wall Street Journal, April 17, 1995; “Scholars Speak Out on Cambodian Holocaust,” Wall Street Journal, July 13, 1995. Other attacks and responses appeared on April 28, May 15 and 30, June 15, and July 13, 1995. For a description and correction of my views on the Khmer Rouge before 1978, see Kiernan, “Vietnam and the Governments and People of Kampuchea,” Bulletin of Concerned Asian Scholars 11:4 (1979): 19-25; 12:2 (1980): 72. 10. Khmer Rouge radio broadcast, August 14, 1995. U.S. CIA, Foreign Broadcast Information Service, EAS-95-157, August 15, 1995: 67. The Khmer Rouge also described me as “a protégé of the United States.” 11. “America’s Cambodian Coda,” Asian Wall Street Journal, October 29, 1996. 12. “Will Yale Deliver?” Wall Street Journal, December 19, 1996. For a different view of the CGP, see “Cambodia’s Blinding Genocide: A Website Exhumes the Faces of the Dead,” New York Times Editorial Notebook, April 21, 1997. 13. Unpublished letters to the Wall Street Journal in response to its December 19, 1996, article and editorial on the CGP can be found at its World Wide Web site (www.yale.edu/cgp), under “More Findings”: “CGP Assistance to the Search for US MIA’s.” 14. On academic suppression, see for instance Brian Martin et al., eds., Intellectual Suppres- sion: Australian Case Histories, Analysis, and Responses (Sydney: Angus and Robertson, 1986). 15. Letter to the editor, Far Eastern Economic Review (FEER), July 5, 1984. Bunroeun Thach later moved to the University of Hawaii; see his “Two Eggs in the Same Baskets,” Khmer Conscience (Winter 1991), my reply, “Bunroeun Thach’s Basket Case,” and the subsequent exchange (Spring-Summer 1991): 19-23. Thach later became Acting Director of the Preah Kiernan 105 Sihanouk Raj Academy in Phnom Penh, but his incompetence and racism created internal strife and controversy. In 1995 King Sihanouk withdrew his endorsement for the Acad- emy. Thach was dismissed and left Cambodia, and the Academy re-formed as the Center for Advanced Study. 16. Steve Sharp, “Sites of Genocide,” Good Weekend, March 29, 1997: 33-34, 37. 17. Holocaust and Genocide Studies (Winter 1997): 413-425; the quotations appear on pp. 414, 416, 420, 423, respectively. 18. For contrary evidence which Sorpong Peou deliberately ignored in his review, see The Pol Pot Regime, 67-68, 258-267, and 93, respectively; and my response, Holocaust and Genocide Studies (Summer 1998). 19. Stephen R. Heder, “Khmer Rouge Opposition to Pol Pot,” in Reflections on Cambodian Po- litical History, Australian National University, Strategic and Defence Studies Center, Working Paper no. 239, 1991: 5. 20. Keith Richburg, “Timing of Khmer Rouge Defections Suggests Possible Role by China,” Washington Post, August 24, 1996: A18. 21. Phnom Penh Post, October 18 and November 1, 1996. 22. Former Khmer Rouge official Suong Sikoeun, Phnom Penh Post, November 15-28, 1996, quoting Stephen Heder on Radio France-Internationale, August 22 and October 10, 1996. 23. Stephen R. Heder, Pol Pot and Khieu Samphan, Monash University, Centre of Southeast Asian Studies, Working Paper no. 70: 22-23. 24 . “Evidence Against K. Rouge Leaders Varies—Researcher,” News America Digital Publish- ing, Phnom Penh, January 5, 1999, wire report distributed on Camnews, January 5, 1999. 25. Gregory Stanton, personal communication. 26. Pol Pot Plans the Future, 7. 27. Khieu Samphan, speech broadcast on Phnom Penh Radio, April 15, 1977, extract in New Statesman, May 2, 1980: 675. 28. See Ieng Sary’s Regime: A Diary of the Khmer Rouge Foreign Ministry, 1976-79, full transla- tion by Phat Kosal and Ben Kiernan available on the Cambodian Genocide Program website (www.yale.edu/cgp). 29. See Michael Vickery, Cambodia 1975-1982 (Boston: South End Press, 1984); David P. Chan- dler, The Tragedy of Cambodian History (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1991), 3; David Chandler, Brother Number One (Boulder, CO: Westview, 1992), 4-5, and Journal of Asian Studies 55:4 (November 1996): 1063-1064. 30. Michael Vickery, “Violence in Democratic Kampuchea,” paper distributed at a conference on State-Organized Terror, Michigan State University, November 1988: 14; and Vickery, Cambodia 1975-1982, 289-90. He correctly adds: “DK theory had multiple origins, one of which was ‘Thanhism’ and another of which was Marxism. It is not easy to say which became of greater importance in the synthesis” (p. 256). 31. Vickery, “Violence in Democratic Kampuchea,” 17. 32. Chandler, The Tragedy of Cambodian History, 1. He correctly adds: “This does nothing to alleviate the horror or their responsibility for it.” 33. For my critique of Vickery’s and Chandler’s views, see Ben Kiernan, The Pol Pot Regime: Race, Power, and Genocide in Cambodia under the Khmer Rouge, 1975-1979, (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1996), and my review in the Journal of Asian Studies 52:4 (November 1993): 1076-78. 34. See Serge Thion, Vérité historique ou vérité politique: affaire Faurisson (Paris: La Vieille Taupe, 1980). 35. For instance, Serge Thion, “Genocide as a Political Commodity,” in Genocide and Democracy in Cambodia: The Khmer Rouge, the United Nations, and the International Caommunity, ed. Ben Kiernan (New Haven, CT: Yale Council on Southeast Asia Studies, 1993), esp. 187: “We should first clean our own house....Who are we to give moral lessons to others?” Thion’s premise is that all Westerners are responsible for U.S. or French government war crimes, an immobilizing notion of Caucasian collective guilt. A harsher view is that he also had no expectations of his appeal for a Cambodian domestic tribunal. (For my critique of Thion’s view of the Cambodian genocide itself, see p. 17.) 36. Vickery, Cambodia 1975-1982, 287 ; Chandler, Brother Number One, 3. 106 Human Rights Review, April-June 2000 37. Julio A. Jeldres, “A Response to Michael Vickery,” distributed by Hann So, Camnews Internet discussion list, June 17, 1996. 38. See Private Eye (London), May 7 and July 16, 1993; Phnom Penh Post, November 30, 1996; and below. 39. Julio A. Jeldres, “Genocide Investigation off on the Wrong Foot,” Cambodia Daily, January 27, 1995. 40. Ben Kiernan, “Jeldres Wrong to Point Finger at Alleged ‘Pol Pot Apologists,’” Cambodia Daily, February 1, 1995. I added that in less than a year (in 1977-78) Jeldres had received three invitations to visit the Chilean consulate in Sydney, Australia. I was aware of this because Jeldres had written to me at the time (on March 14, 1978), revealing also that “the programmes were rather heavy and I did not have a minute to spare.” These three invita- tions followed Jeldres’ earlier visit to the Chilean consulate in May 1977. 41. “Jeldres vs. Kiernan,” Cambodia Daily, February 10, 1995, and Rosanna Barbero, “Jeldres Falls into His Own Trap,” Cambodia Daily, February 14, 1995. 42. Australia, Jeldres went on, “has now joined the communist countries and the so-called non-aligned ones in their attacks against Chile. We are getting sanctions because we did not want a communist government. The change of government in Chile is our problem and not Australia’s.” Julio A. Jeldres, “Insult to Chile,” Melbourne Age, January 21, 1975. For the Wall Street Journal editorial page’s defense of Pinochet, see Extra! 8:5 (September/ October 1995): 15, 19; and of mass murder in El Salvador, 14-18. 43. In a letter to the author dated July 1, 1976, Jeldres revealed that, “In 1971, I was made Honorary Member of FUNK”; copy in my possession. FUNK was the Front Uni National du Kampuchéa, a coalition of Sihanoukists and Khmer Rouge dominated by the latter. 44. Jeldres, letter to the author dated March 14, 1978; copy in my possession. 45. Cambodia Daily, February 10, 1995. 46. Far Eastern Economic Review, May 31, 1984. See my reply to Jeldres of June 21, 1984. 47. William Shawcross denied Jeldres’ association with Khmer Conscience (see Private Eye, July 2 and 16, 1993), but its editor Hann So continued to distribute Jeldres’ writings. See Jeldres, “A Response to Michael Vickery,” distributed by Hann So, Camnews discussion list, June 17, 1996, copy in my possession. 48. See, for instance, Jeldres’ articles in Cambodia Daily, February 28, 1995, and Phnom Penh Post, July 28, 1995 and September 20, 1996; also Jeldres’ statements on Radio Australia, September 13, 1995. 49. In 1996 Jeldres revealed: “I met Stephen Morris twice in Bangkok in 1985/86....I have since spoken to him three times on the phone” (Jeldres, “Response to Michael Vickery,” distrib- uted by Hann So, Camnews discussion list, June 17, 1996). 50. “Thailand’s Separate Peace in Indochina,” Asian Wall Street Journal, September 4, 1989. 51. Mary Scully, R.N.C.S., and Theanvy Kuoch, unpublished letter to the Wall Street Journal, May 19, 1995. 52. Morris argued further that the Khmer Rouge were not the problem: “The danger lies in the Vietnamese Communists’ determination to subvert such an agreement.” Stephen J. Mor- ris, “Skeletons in the Closet,” New Republic, June 4, 1990. Morris labeled critics of the UN plan, and of its inclusion of the Khmer Rouge, as proponents of “an immoral, lost cause” beholden to Hanoi. The UN plan, he asserted, “is morally right, and offers real hope of success.” It gave the Khmer Rouge, Morris wrongly predicted, an “incentive to lay down its arms,” which “will end the war.” Morris, “US Choice in Cambodia,” Boston Globe, August 7, 1990. 53. Morris had once described Cornell University’s Southeast Asia Program (America’s most distinguished such institution) as “a comfortable milieu for those fond of totalitarian dic- tatorship.” Morris attacked Heder, a former Cornell student, for his “pro-Khmer Rouge views” and for “propounding the moral virtue” of communism (Stephen J. Morris, “Ho Chi Minh, Pol Pot, and Cornell,” National Interest (Summer 1989): 60). But in 1995, Morris shamelessly recommended Heder as one of a team he suggested should have been awarded the State Department grant that I received to document the crimes of the Khmer Rouge (Asian Wall Street Journal, April 17, 1995). In one of his own attacks on my work, Heder cited an unpublished draft by Morris (Southeast Asia Research 5:2 (July 1997): 128, n. 57). Kiernan 107 Though François Ponchaud also described Heder as “un Américain pro-Khmers Rouges” (Le Point, April 25, 1998), Henri Locard has cited Heder’s work to attack mine. Locard asserted inter alia that the Khmer Rouge were “sincere idealistic leaders” and had not massacred Cambodia’s Vietnamese minority, but had expelled and “spared” them (Le Monde, April 28, 1998). See my response (Le Monde, May 14, 1998), and my article, “Le communisme racial des Khmer rouges,” Esprit 252 (May 1999): 93-127. 54. Morris, “ABC Flacks for Hanoi,” Wall Street Journal, April 26, 1990. 55. Wall Street Journal, June 6, 1990. Morris has a history of McCarthyist witch-hunting. Once affiliated with Harvard’s Russian Research Center, Morris fell out with its Associate Direc- tor, Professor Marshall Goldman, whom Morris calls an “ally” of “the pro-Hanoi left” (Wash- ington Times, September 29, 1993). Neil Sheehan, author of the Pulitzer Prize-winning work, A Bright Shining Lie: John Paul Vann and the Americans in Vietnam, is dismissed by Morris as someone who “holds a benign view of the Vietnamese Communist Party” (Wash- ington Times, September 29, 1993). John McAuliff and Eileen Blumenthal, organizers of a 1990 Cambodian dancers’ tour of the United States, were attacked by Morris for possible “criminal” activity (Boston Globe, October 14, 1990) and for holding 39 dancers as “prison- ers.” Morris’s charges were investigated and proved to be totally unfounded by both the State Department and the Immigration and Naturalization Service. McAuliff’s and Blumenthal’s alleged victims, in both Cambodia and the U.S., remain their colleagues and friends (letter to the Wall Street Journal, April 28, 1995). 56. “Scholars Speak Out on Cambodia Holocaust,” Wall Street Journal, July 13, 1995. See also Washington Post, July 8, 1995. 57. See John Kifner, “Lott, and Shadow of a Pro-White Group,” New York Times, January 14, 1999: A9; Frank Rich, “Scandals Sans Bimbos Need Not Apply,” New York Times, December 26, 1998: A27; People For the American Way, PFAW News (Winter 1999): 5. 58. Alphonse La Porta, personal communication, August 22, 1995. 59. “The Academic Killing Fields,” Washington Times, October 2, 1995. 60. See for instance, Eyal Press, “Unforgiven,” Lingua Franca (April/May 1997): 72. A letter to the Secretary of State from Rep. Martin Hoke of Ohio, backing Morris’ charges and circu- lated to the 435 members of Congress, drew only one signatory, that of Robert K. Dornan of California (June 19, 1995). 61. Copies of Wold’s and my letters can be found at the CGP’s World Wide Web site (www.yale.edu/cgp), under More Findings: “CGP Assistance to the Search for US MIA’s.” 62. Chandler e-mailed me on November 19, 1996: “Thanks for your supportive response to the MIA people, with whom I’ll be working in Phnom Penh in Jan.-Feb.” 63. Nancy DeWolf Smith, “America’s Cambodian Coda,” Asian Wall Street Journal, October 29, 1996. 64. For evidence of Melloan’s McCarthyist false charges against journalist Raymond Bonner on El Salvador, see Extra! 8:5 (September-October 1995): 15. 65. “Will Yale Deliver?” Wall Street Journal, December 19, 1996. 66. “Will Yale Deliver?” Asian Wall Street Journal, December 20, 1996. 67. For the facts, see the unpublished letters posted on the CGP’s website (www.yale.edu/ cgp). 68. The Cambodian Genocide Data Base and other materials on the Khmer Rouge can be found at www.yale.edu/cgp. 69. Peter Michelmore, “Legacy of the Killing Fields,” Reader’s Digest (May 1997): 66. See also Chanthou Boua and Ben Kiernan, “Bureaucracy of Death: Documents from Inside Pol Pot’s Torture Machine,” New Statesman, May 2, 1980. 70. See Cambodia Daily, September 10-11, 1996. 71. Letter to the author from the Inspector-General, Jacquelyn L. Williams-Bridgers, dated November 5, 1998. 72. Statement by Rep. Dana Rohrabacher (R-Ca) on the House floor, October 10, 1998, quoted in Indochina Interchange 9:1 (Winter 1999): 14. 73. Stephen J. Morris, “Clinton’s Genocide Confusion,” Commentary, January 12, 1999. 74. Adam Garfinkle, “Be Careful Which Graves We Exhume,” Los Angeles Times, January 24, 1999. 108 Human Rights Review, April-June 2000 75. H. Bruce Franklin, M.I.A. or Mythmaking in America (New York, Lawrence Hill, 1992). Stephen Morris’ claimed 1993 “find” of an alleged Russian document on U.S. POWs in Vietnam was quickly shown to be full of errors (Nayan Chanda, “Research and Destroy,” Far Eastern Economic Review, May 6, 1993), and was reported to be a CIA fake (Susan Katz Keating, Prisoners of Hope, 1994). work_62flh5fadrbzlmsehqzqngptiq ---- Emotions and criminal justice S U S A N N E K A R S T E D T Keele University, UK Abstract During the last decade, a process of ‘emotionalization of law’ has spread around the globe, changing the criminal justice system in many ways. Anger, disgust and shame are perceived as ‘valuable barometers of social morality’ and brought back to criminal procedures. The ‘return of emotions’ to penal law and criminal justice is linked to and illuminates the moral imagination of late modern societies. This article seeks to address two facets of the ‘return of emotions’ to criminal justice. The first part explores the changes in the public sphere and in the pattern of emotional culture in late modern societies that are responsible for the re- emotionalization of the penal realm. In the second part, problems that emerge in the criminal justice system are addressed. Bringing emotions back involves profound problems that go beyond the mere instrumental use of emotions in criminal justice, or a restricted perspective of ‘what works’. Three ‘core’ problems—and associated—questions are discussed: first, are emotional reactions towards crimes ‘natural’ or ‘primordial’ such that they should occupy a prominent place in criminal justice that has been unduly ignored? Second, and relatedly, do emotions constitute our moral principles? Finally, should institutions elicit or even require ‘authentic emotions’ from individuals? These questions are addressed within the framework of contemporary emotion theory and the consequences of this perspective for the ‘use’ of emotions in criminal justice are discussed. Key Words emotion • emotionalization • emotion theory • late modernity • penal law Theoretical Criminology © 2002 SAGE Publications London, Thousand Oaks and New Delhi. 1362–4806(200208)6:3 Vol. 6(3): 299–317; 026025 299 http:\\www.sagepublications.com Emotions and penal law Emotions pervade penal law and the criminal justice system. Offenders, victims and witnesses bring their emotions to the courtroom, criminal courts deal with crimes of passion, and their decisions can occasion public outrage and anger, or feelings of vengeance among victims. Offenders feel shame and remorse when they have transgressed the laws, and offences provoke feelings of moral disgust. At the same time, victims as well as offenders elicit our compassion and sympathy. Law has by no means been blind to this invasion of emotions into its very realm. It explicitly references and grants legitimacy to emotions through legal defences (as in crimes of passion); by establishing specific categories of behaviour like ‘hate crimes’, or by restricting the admission of evidence that might influence the emotions of jury members and judges (as, for example, in victim statements—see Posner, 2000). Legal institutions and in particular the criminal justice system are the very institutions in society that are designed to deal with the most intense emotions and emotional conflicts, with individual as well as collective emotions. The criminal courts and procedures are a prominent institutional space and institutional mechanism for emotions in society.1 The particular position of penal law and the criminal justice system in the emotional space delineated by societies has long since captured the imagination of social theorists, and figures prominently in the work of Durkheim and Elias. Both realized that penal law was deeply embedded in the emotional culture of societies, and intricately linked to the structural and institutional patterns of society. Consequently, decisive changes in the ‘morality’ (Durkheim) and ‘mentality’ (Elias) of societies are at the roots of the historical development of penal law and punishment, and criminal justice illuminates—or more technically, indicates—subterranean shifts in the emotional culture of societies. Interestingly, both of these theorists interpreted the historical change from traditional to modern society as a pathway that continuously and consistently limited and changed the role of emotions in the public sphere, and, as a result, modes of penal law and punishment. Modern societies, highly differentiated and interdependent, rely on other and more subtle mechanisms to ensure compliance with norms than the crude and simple arousal of moral and collective emotions by criminal proceedings and the (public) execution of sanctions. In jurisprudence, the history of penal law and criminal justice is in fact cast as a process that has more strictly confined and more precisely outlined the space of emotions, and limited the amount of emotionality that is admitted in courts. The conventional story of modern penal law portrays a narrowly delineated list and proper roles for emotions in the legal realm, so that emotions do not intrude into the true preserve of law: reason (Bandes, 1999a: 2). Such a juxtaposition of reason and emotion, one deeply embedded in modern thought, seems within the normative framework of Theoretical Criminology 6(3)300 jurisprudence to ignore vital facets of the actual role of emotions in law and legal procedures (see Douglas, 1993). The edifice of penal law itself is erected on a strong undercurrent of emotions: the fear of sanctions, that should instil compliance, or vengeance that is to be channelled by legal procedures (Elster, 1999). Popular wisdom as well as criminological theory have both established fear of sanctions as a cornerstone and powerful mechanism of the criminal justice system, the thing that makes it work. Far from precluding rational action, emotions may facilitate a ‘rational response’—for example, to the experience of injustice. The ‘handling of emotions’ within the criminal justice system is not a priori ‘rational’, neither in its procedural arrangements nor with regard to its final out- comes, but designed according to specific functions. Both offenders and victims react by no means in principle emotionally, but make ‘rational decisions’ when dealing with the criminal justice system: offenders try to find ways of beating the system, or victims weigh the advantages and disadvantages of invoking the law (Poletta, 2001).2 During the last decade, the secular process of restricting the space of emotions in the penal realm seems to have taken a turn towards bringing emotions back in. A process of ‘re-emotionalization of law’ or the ‘reasser- tion of emotionality in law’ (Laster and O’Malley, 1996) spread around the globe, and has changed the criminal justice system in many ways. The ‘return of emotions’ to criminal justice and penal policies has occurred in two arenas: the emotionalization of public discourse about crime and criminal justice, and the implementation of sanctions in the criminal justice system that are explicitly based on—or designed to arouse—emotions. Both developments corresponded to the changing space of emotions and the emotional culture of late modern societies, and it can be assumed that these processes have fuelled one another. This article seeks to address both these facets of the ‘return of emotions’ to criminal justice. In the first part, I argue that changes in the public sphere and emotional culture of late modern societies are responsible for the re- emotionalization of the penal realm. In the second part, I address the problems that consequently emerge in the criminal justice system. Bringing emotions back involves profound problems that go beyond the mere instrumental use of emotions in criminal justice, or a restricted perspective of ‘what works’. I will discuss three ‘core’ problems and a series of associated questions: first, are emotional reactions towards crimes ‘natural’ or ‘primordial’, such that they need not only a proper but a prominent place in criminal justice which has been unduly ignored? Second, and relatedly, do emotions constitute our moral principles? Finally, I deal with a series of questions concerning the invisibility of emotions; should institu- tions elicit or even require ‘authentic emotions’ from individuals? What is the different role and impact of emotions in criminal justice in a culture which ritualizes emotional expression or promotes individualistic, Karstedt—Emotions and criminal justice 301 authentic expression? These questions will be addressed within the frame- work of contemporary emotion theory. The ‘return of emotions’ ‘The Return of Shame’—as described in a Newsweek article in 1995—has brought back an emotion to the criminal justice system that had been dismissed as hopelessly old-fashioned during previous decades. Judges in the United States were the first to remake the courts and the criminal justice system as a public space of emotions. Offenders were ordered by courts to wear T-shirts in public that identified them as thieves. Young offenders had to apologize on their knees to their victims with members of the community present. Sexual offenders had to erect signs on their front lawn warning the public about the inhabitant; another court order sent the victims of a burglary to the house of the offender to take from it what they liked (see Massaro, 1991, 1997; Anderson, 1995; Karstedt, 1996). What is striking about these sentences, is not only the explicit use of emotion, but the way it is done, the great emphasis placed on their publicness. The thin line between shame, humiliation and stigmatization was consistently ignored, and the question of whether shame has the impact intended if imposed in such ways never asked (see Elster, 1999: 145). The effects of constant and public terrorization of norm-violators by an emotional mechanism (which the judges assumed to be shame) on the offender and/or watching specta- tors was never questioned in these cases. The revival of shame in the first instance came with ‘episodic, almost whimsical bursts of judicial, legislative or prosecutorial inspiration’ (Massaro, 1991: 1940), which were nonethe- less the first and most visible signs of the return of emotions. The influential movement of restorative justice in criminology and criminal justice is based in contrast on a theoretical concept. In his book Crime, Shame and Reintegration (1989), Braithwaite carefully developed a theoretical argument to the effect that shaming the offence, but not the offender, will reintegrate the offender into the community. In indigenous procedures of ‘conferencing’ from New Zealand and Australia he found settings in which shaming and reintegration could simultaneously work.3 In particular, he gave the victims a strong role and presence in these procedures. Their participation should make the process of shaming powerful and lasting. The conferences were designed to allow for emotional experiences and expressions of shame, remorse, guilt and anger, but also of sympathy and forgiveness. The fact that procedures of re- storative justice have become the most successful reform movement in criminal justice world-wide shows that the return of emotions has struck a cord in the criminal justice system and with the public. In instances as diverse as drunk driving, teenage shoplifting and domestic violence (as well as in the Truth and Reconciliation Commissions for perpetrators of past regimes) emotions were brought back into legal procedures and made an Theoretical Criminology 6(3)302 essential part of them. While restorative justice brought victims to centre- stage, it made it perfectly clear that justice is relational, something that establishes an emotional connection between the victim, the offender and the often neglected actors who actually impose the punishment (see Elster, 1989; Karstedt, 1993). Criminology and jurisprudence have rediscovered both individual and collective emotions (Skillen, 1980; Pratt, 2000; Freiberg, 2001). Leading figures in the economic analysis of law (Posner, 2000) have turned to emotions, and discovered that ‘the violation of norms triggers strong, emotional reactions, in the offender as well as in others’ (Elster, 1989: 100). But it comes as a striking fact that the ‘moral sentiments’ identified by most of these authors as the foundations of law are what can be termed ‘negative emotions’ (Solomon, 1990; Bandes, 1999b; Kahan, 1999; Posner, 2000). Moral disgust, revulsion and feelings of vengeance are found to be ‘valua- ble barometers of societal morality’ (Bandes, 1999a: 4), serving as a legitimate foundation for law and legal procedures. This stands in stark contrast to early theories on moral sentiments found in the writings of Adam Smith, Hume and Hutcheson. These authors embedded the moral bond in emotions of sympathy and empathy, wherein the ‘strong senti- ments of morals’ are based on ‘indignation’ as well as ‘tender-heartedness’ (see, for a discussion, Solomon, 1990, 1994; Boltanski, 1999). These developments are in line with changes in public and political discourse about crime, and take up the process of emotionalization that is characteristic of the public sphere of late modernity. The return of shame, restorative justice and the emotionalization of public discourse about crime and law, are responding to changes in wider emotional culture, and changing the moral imagination of these societies. The media engage their public in ‘distant suffering’ (Boltanski, 1999)—compassion and sympathy with victims, expressions of moral disgust towards offences and the perpetrators. An intensely emotional discourse about crime thus comes to be fuelled by the most recent and most heinous offence. Crime policies are explicitly based on the expression of collective emotions of fear and anger about crime. Politicians compete with each other in addressing the ‘emo- tional’ needs of the public, and in turn mirror these emotions back to the audience and the electorate. National and even global audiences become highly emotionalized ‘moral spectators’ in the spectacles of distant suffer- ing of victims and perpetrators. In a public sphere constituted by distant suffering, and the emotions it arouses and the moral commitment it induces, the task of criminal justice is extremely simplified: justice for victims means making offenders suffer the harshest punishment available. But as Boltanski shows, social distance and what Hirschman calls ‘benevolent disinterest’ are nonetheless required from truly moral spectators. They have to show a certain amount of impartiality and even, paradoxically, indifference if their emotions and moral commitment are to become authentic (Boltanski, 1999; Karstedt, 2000). The emotionalized discourse about crime and criminal justice in the Karstedt—Emotions and criminal justice 303 public sphere is defined by the absence of such indifference and impartial- ity. Even if we do not agree with Charles Taylor (1992) that ‘victimization’ is the defining feature of public discourse in late modernity, a certain imbalance of public interest, moral commitment and compassion towards the victim is obvious.4 In Britain, public demands for representation of the emotions of victims in the criminal justice system have been widely supported. Their sorrow, rage and anger, and feelings of vengeance need to be voiced, and ‘healed’ by the sanction imposed on the offender. This imbalance in the collective emotional mood thus easily intrudes in- to the criminal justice system, where decisions disadvantage actual offenders. The social context in which these developments take place is the increas- ingly emotionalized cultures of late modern societies (see Wouters, 1986; Vester, 1991; Barbalet, 1998; Neckel, 1999; Williams, 2001).5 Modern societies clearly stress individual autonomy and individual self-representa- tion. This includes the open display of emotions and the claim that these have to be considered as singular and authentic expressions of the auton- omy and identity of the individual. The significance of the expression of emotions corresponds to the importance of emotional experiences and fulfilment. Cross-cultural research shows that individuals are more risk- taking and thrill-seeking—both intense emotional experiences—in modern societies than in more traditional ones (Triandis, 1994; Karstedt, 2001). At the same time, individualization in the display of emotions and emotionality is juxtaposed by an extremely distant emotionality that characterizes the public sphere, the aforementioned feature of ‘distant suffering’. The media bring home the ‘spectacle’ of suffering to very diffused spectators, and elicit strong emotional reactions like sorrow, rage, anger and compassion.6 Social movements and organizations try to convert these emotions into participation in their tasks and targets. Such distant moral sentiments are no longer embedded in direct interactions between individuals or in the social space of communities. As such they lack mutuality and duration, and become more fleeting and volatile. The objects of our compassion, anger and fear change quickly, the media operating with a keen sense of the half-life of emotional arousal in the public sphere. Between the individualization of emotionality on the one hand, and distant emotionality on the other, the emotional space of groups seems to have been eroded. Joint experiences of emotions, emotions which are embedded in group rituals and the display of collective identity are not common in late modern societies. More often they take the form of deviant reactions—such as rioting or football hooliganism—when rage and anger is vented (see Dunning et al., 1986; Dunning, 1992; Frijda, 1996). The criminal law and criminal justice system respond to the bi-partite nature of emotionality in modern societies, on the one hand by opening up more space for the expression of individual emotions, on the other by increas- ingly responding to public and collective emotions. It comes as no surprise Theoretical Criminology 6(3)304 that shame has played a prominent role in this process, since this emotion establishes a link between the individual and the public sphere. Three core problems I want to explore the core problems and questions I outlined earlier using three exemplary ‘stories’. The first two of these illuminate problems and questions related to the nature of the link between emotions, law and morality. Is the criminal justice system linked to and founded on basic emotional reactions towards crimes and offenders, and are such basic emotions constitutive of morality? When I came to the UK in June 2000, I was soon confronted with a tabloid-led campaign of ‘naming and shaming’ paedophiles that followed the abduction and murder of 8-year-old Sarah Payne. The public reacted with an extreme display of emotions: strangers left flowers and teddy bears at the site where Sarah Payne’s body had been found, the service became a media spectacle of outbursts of emotions, and vengeful groups gathered before the houses of those who had been named in a newspaper campaign as paedophiles. This differed considerably from what had taken place in Germany in a very similar case only a year before. Thousands of men had (more or less) voluntarily enlisted for a genetic test (by which route the offender was ultimately found), but the public display of emotional reac- tions was not comparable to what had taken place in Britain. Emotional practices in public reactions towards crime are obviously and decisively shaped by specific emotional cultures and their institutional settings (such as modal national character, specific models, or characteristic features of the legal and political system), even if the cultures are otherwise very similar—as is the case with Britain and Germany—in their general emotional reactions (Mesquita et al., 1997; Mikula et al., 1998). This suggests that criminal justice is not based on specific basic emotions that are ‘primordial’ to its existence, but, rather, that the specific institutional and cultural pattern in which these emotions are embedded constitute and define the emotional reaction. Emotions seem to be only loosely coupled to the institutional framework which gives space to a diversity of emotions and emotional practices. The spontaneity of the public’s emotional reaction in Britain confirms more a well-established cultural pattern than a col- lective ‘natural response’. My second exemplary story explores further the problem of basic emotions and their constitutive role in criminal justice. It was written by Plato in his Socratic dialogue ‘Protagoras’ (1987) nearly 2400 years ago. At the dawn of humankind, human beings were incapable of living together, their cities torn with violence and strife. Thus, Zeus feared that humankind was in danger of utter destruction. He sent his messenger who was, Karstedt—Emotions and criminal justice 305 remarkably, the god both of merchants and thieves, down to earth with two gifts that should enable humankind successfully to establish commu- nities and live together safely and amicably. These two gifts were shame and law, and Zeus gave orders to his messenger to distribute them equally among human beings. Thus, they were equally endowed with a ‘moral sense’ which was based on a strong emotion and gave them the capacity of autonomous moral judgements and, simultaneously, with a framework of common norms and principles. It is clear that Plato posits a basic emotion—shame—as the foundation of morality and law, exactly the one that has figured prominently in the late modern return of emotions. Nonetheless, the link is not clear, and there are several types. Braithwaite adopts a position which can be described as ‘functionalist’, as for him shame as a moral sentiment has two functions in producing compliance: it inhibits people from transgressing the moral norms and laws, and it establishes the self as a moral self in one’s own and others’ eyes. According to the ‘constitutive’ position (Taylor, 1987) moral sentiments provide the motivation to comply with moral norms. Morality is based on the capacity of individuals to feel shame after having trans- gressed the norms, and accordingly the moral sentiment constitutes moral action. The ‘indicative’ link between emotions and morality establishes a relationship in which emotions are only the consequence or expression of moral engagement in one’s own actions or those of others, and of moral principles which have been accepted. Moral sentiments are neither con- stitutive nor a motivation for moral action, but are attached to a moral principle and judgement (see Nunner-Winkler, 1998). This is essentially the position of Durkheim, that strong moral sentiments indicate strong moral norms, and reinforce these norms following their violation. My final exemplary story explores a problem, one that becomes im- portant when emotions return to criminal justice in an emotional culture, concerning the authenticity of emotions: their invisibility.7 In 1517, Martin Luther started Reformation in Germany by hammering his 95 propositions to the door of the church in Wittenberg. In about one-third of them, Luther argued that no institution could and should interfere with individual repentance, and feelings of shame and guilt, let alone use or exploit them for institutional purposes. Interestingly, in some of his main arguments he contended that only God—not even always the offender—could know if these feelings were authentic and truthful (Luther, undated). What is important here is not that this was one of the many steps on the way towards individualism and modernity, but that Luther was aware of the invisibility of emotions and the problems this fact causes for any social institution that deals with them. How can we know that offenders really feel shame and remorse in restorative justice conferences? How ‘true’ are expressions of anger voiced by victims? Would we rate a restorative justice conference less successful if everyone present only pretended his/her feel- ings, or would we rely on their actions, or the final outcome? How fearful Theoretical Criminology 6(3)306 or angry are victims really, or do emotional public responses to, and demands for action against, crime (as witnessed in the campaign for ‘Sarah’s Law’) merely indicate a public caught up in media and political scripts?8 Obviously, the quest for authentic emotions in late modern societies and the fact that they are ‘invisible’ contradict each other, and even in societies where the authentic display of emotions is demanded and rewarded, people will hide many if not most of them. Significantly, shame cultures have ritualized and formalized the expression of shame, authenticity is not requested and the strength of emotions is not relevant. It is hard to discern if that has an impact on the intensity of the emotion. In the absence of such formalized emotional practices, the return of shame resulted in sentences and practices which tried to elicit an intense and authentic feeling of shame, and there were few restrictions on how that was achieved. Answers to these questions and solutions to these problems will define the role and the space of emotions in criminal justice. Contemporary psychological theory has in particular addressed the problems of basic and universal emotions, how emotions are linked to social settings and the way cultural practices influence, regulate and define emotions. Perspectives from contemporary emotion theory Though an extremely diverse field, contemporary emotion theory does not conceptualize emotions as ‘unitary, elementary entities’ but instead as ‘multi-componential phenomena’.9 Rather than assuming homogenous emotional states and a definite number of basic and universal emotions, emotion processes consisting of ‘concurrent changes in several different components’ are of central importance, thus making emotions dynamic. Such a perspective is based on the notion that human beings have a universal emotional potential, but that this is realized in actual emotional practices, and in concrete social and cultural settings. Across cultures, emotions like anger and fear, or disgust and shame therefore simultane- ously can be similar in some respects, and different in others. Expressions of emotions will vary from culture to culture even if they have a universal base. Thus, universal recognition of a particular facial expression as depicting anger, or blushing as a sign of shame, does not rule out the possibility that the counterparts of both emotions in other cultures may be different in those events that arouse them, and with regard to the actual emotional practices in which they are embedded. This applies equally to different contexts within a culture. The components of an emotion do not automatically follow from each other or from context-specific character- istics. A procedure explicitly designed to arouse shame may equally arouse feelings of humiliation and anger. Universality of emotions therefore can be Karstedt—Emotions and criminal justice 307 ‘established only for components of emotions rather than for emotions as a whole’ (Mesquita et al., 1997: 259–60). The emotion process (see Figure 1) includes the following components: an antecedent event, an emotional experience and an appraisal of the event, physiological change and change in action readiness, a specific behaviour or emotional practice, a change in cognitive functioning and beliefs and a regulatory process which determines its course. The intensity and ‘power’ of emotions (Frijda, 1996), drastic action impulses, long duration of feelings as in revenge (Frijda, 1994) or profound changes in beliefs, are caused by the interaction of these components and the strength of emotions built up during the process. Emotions result from individual concerns that are essential in the definition and appraisal of a situation. In particular, individual goals, motives and values that relate individuals with social and common con- cerns emerge when an event is appraised as harming or threatening. Concerns like prestige and self-esteem, or the sense of belonging are linked to emotions of pride and shame. Concern for identity and autonomy arouses intense feelings of anger if not treated with respect and recognition, and being shamed is a most powerful source of rage and feelings of revenge. Research on ghetto youths has established the close link between violent behaviour and the ‘search for respect’ (Bourgois, 1995). Most important here is the fact that individual concerns are derived from social values and common or even universal concerns, and thus link Figure 1 Component-process-model of emotions Source: Adapted from Frijda (1996) Theoretical Criminology 6(3)308 individual and collective emotions. Concerns arise from social and moral values of justice and fairness, which are universal to all cultures (see Schwartz, 1992, 1994; Schwartz and Sagiv, 1995). Concerns about basic moral principles are affected when these are injured. The collective nature of such concerns implies that not only individual experiences but equally experiences of others are events that are linked to emotions of anger as well as sympathy and compassion. Regulation rules are a component of the emotion process that are particularly important for the development of shared emotional practices. They control and inhibit the display of emotions, they define the proper social space for emotions, and they restrict emotional action. The role of regulation rules becomes obvious when control is lifted within the social environment: when collective expressions of anger and disgust are en- couraged, articulation of hatred is rewarded, or revenge is subtly praised (Frijda, 1996: 20). Regulation rules define the importance of emotions of victims, and the amount of display in social space, and they equally restrict the emotional space of offenders. Legal procedures provide an elaborately regulated space for emotions. What then are the implications of contemporary emotion theory for the core problems of primordial emotions, basic emotions and the link between emotions, morality and the law? One of the most important conclusions from contemporary emotion theory is that penal law and legal procedures are not built on ‘basic emotions’, but are part of the emotion process. They establish an institu- tional context and regulatory processes for a diversity of emotional compo- nents. In particular, legal procedures have the task of establishing those rules of justice and fairness that prevent additional arousal of emotions of anger and feelings of revenge, and that enhance the acceptance of the legal and moral judgment by the offender and the victim. Evidence from research on procedural justice shows that violations of these basic rules arouse those feelings, and as a consequence, decrease the readiness of offenders to accept the judgment and the moral rationale behind it (Tyler, 1990). Resulting feelings of anger and revenge might change beliefs about the fairness and legitimacy of these institutions profoundly. The most important compo- nents of fairness rules are that offenders can tell ‘their stories’, that they are not humiliated before their own peer group and that their self-esteem is not stripped from them. Cross-cultural research has provided evidence of the universality of these values as well as of their importance in legal proce- dures (Schwartz, 1992). It is highly probable that the ‘return of shame’ to the courtrooms will violate these rules, and arouse much more anger and revenge in those who are treated in this way. Contemporary emotion theory suggests that legal procedures and pun- ishment fulfil different tasks and are linked to different emotion processes. The secular changes of penal sanctions during the last centuries provide ample evidence from history that penal punishments are not linked to Karstedt—Emotions and criminal justice 309 universal and basic moral sentiments, but are embedded into the moral imagination of societies and the context of imagined communities (Ander- son, 1983). The spectacle of public executions obviously aroused thrill and excitement among the crowds, and it took some efforts during the 19th century to make it a more sombre event until they were finally banned from public view (Pratt, 2000). The theory would imply further that a diversity of emotions is involved in the process of punishment, and that different emotions restrict and balance each other. It stresses the situational pattern in which emotions are aroused, and the importance of appraisal processes. Punishment is rarely imposed by those who were victims of the offence, and the emotions involved on the side of those who punish have barely got consideration (but see Elster, 1989). Parents or teachers mostly punish children for what they did to others. The type and severity of the punishment imposed by them therefore results from the social bonds that are established and the emo- tions of love and sympathy attached to them; these function as inhibitors to extremely severe reactions. Research on the expectations and experiences of sanctions by juvenile offenders shows that parents normally do not react in a way that would endanger those bonds, but try instead to secure and confirm these bonds in their reactions to an offence committed by their children (Karstedt, 1989, 1993). Courts and juries that are embedded in communities have hesitated to give death sentences, as in the case of a young woman who had murdered her two children. As long as victims were directly involved in the punishment of offenders, practices of restorative justice prevailed (Braithwaite, 2001). In the present context of the spectacle of ‘distant suffering’ where such bonds do not exist, the lack of inhibiting emotions of sympathy and empathy seems to give way to excessive demands for punishment by ‘moral spectators’. Contemporary emotion theory clearly refutes the notion that moral principles and the edifice of law are erected on basic and universal sentiments, and that the latter constitute these principles. Instead, moral principles and axioms of justice and fairness define the concerns, and thus the events that arouse ‘moral sentiments’. Consequently, emotions like anger and disgust and shame are ‘indicators’ of our moral beliefs and convictions—they do not constitute them. ‘Once established, justice is naturally attached with a strong sentiment of morals’ (Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, cited in Solomon, 1990: 198), but justice needs to be established first. Evidence from longitudinal research on the moral develop- ment of children shows that very young children understand moral princi- ples (right versus wrong) but do not attach moral sentiments to them. These are developed at a later stage, the process of attachment being mostly finalized at the age of 10 (Nunner-Winkler, 1998). In particular, historical change and cultural diversity of emotions of moral disgust show that these emotions are linked to antecedent moral judgments and do not constitute them, as I will discuss in the following section. Theoretical Criminology 6(3)310 Disgust, anger, shame: some cautious notes on the use of emotions in criminal justice The recent discourse about law and emotions has been dominated by three emotions—disgust, anger and shame. Though this discourse lingers between constructionist perspectives and assumptions about ‘primordial’ emotions, between a constitutive, functionalist and indicative role of emotions for law and morality, there is nonetheless a strong consensus that emotions could and should be used in the legal sphere and in lawmaking more than in the past. As noted above, legal theorists have identified disgust as a legitimate and valuable barometer of societal morality (Bandes, 1999a: 4; Kahan, 1999; Posner, 1999, 2000). Disgust should and could have a legitimate place in the legal arena. It has been argued that law should shape the cognitive contents of the emotion by leading us to feel disgust for heinous but not sufficiently punished acts like racial violence or hate crimes (Kahan, 1999; see Poletta, 2001 for a critique). In particular, the latter—more con- structionist—perspective is in line with conclusions from emotion theory. Nonetheless, it has to be stressed here that universal components in the emotion process are embedded into concrete cultural settings which define the content of moral rules, and thus the situations when disgust is elicited. Cross-cultural studies in more than 35 countries show that feelings of disgust are mostly and universally related to moral evaluations and events of violation of moral norms, in contrast to anger, which is related to experiences of injustice (Scherer, 1991, 1997). However, the fuelling of emotions of disgust has led societies to treat marginalized groups as if they were less than human, and in particular has instigated racial violence amounting to genocide (Nussbaum, 1999). In his book Ordinary Men, Browning (1992) shows how the members of a police battalion in occupied Poland voiced their disgust about the Jewish popula- tion, and how they used this emotion in their moral legitimation of the mass murder in which they participated.10 These emotions had been consistently fuelled among the population during the Nazi Regime (and before), and this process was related to laws that step-by-step deprived the Jewish population in Germany of their civil and finally human status. Most infamous in this process were the Nuremberg Laws issued in 1936, which prohibited marriages between Jews and other Germans, and barred Jews from employing German girls in their households and businesses with accompanying propaganda that Jews were paedophiles. Existing moral norms and the emotions attached to them were thus used to direct emotional reactions of disgust towards the marginalized group. Disgust is ‘brazenly and uncompromising judgmental’ (Nussbaum, 1999: 21) and therefore comes with a powerful potential for disruptive and violent consequences. As much as it might be ‘necessary . . . for perceiving and motivating opposition to cruelty’ (Nussbaum, 1999: 21), disgust is also heavily implicated in the commission of cruelty. Using it in the legal realm Karstedt—Emotions and criminal justice 311 as a ‘barometer of social morality’ deprives the law of much of its own potential of establishing justice and fairness. Anger is the emotion most clearly linked to concerns and values about justice and fair treatment (Frijda, 1996; Mesquita et al., 1997; Scherer, 1997). Notwithstanding cultural differences with regard to the intensity and the display of anger, the emotional link seems to be universal. We get angry when we and others are not treated fairly, or are humiliated, or when our social position and self-esteem are hurt. Legal procedures have a central role in society as they provide justice, both channelling such feelings and simultaneously arousing them. Anger of victims of crime might be linked to such a sense of ‘unfair’ treatment by fellow citizens. But it is much less clear how ‘anger about crime’ is aroused in those who have not been a victim and who have no personal experience of crime (Farrall, 2001). What kind of concerns and emotional experiences are involved, and what are the underlying emotion components and processes, when a majority of the population declares that they are ‘angry about crime’? Before designing ‘affective crime prevention policies’ (Freiberg, 2001) that take into account such emotional processes, we need to establish which kind of emotion and emotion process are involved, if at all. Shame, remorse and guilt are emotions most closely linked to the criminal justice system and the community it represents. Among them shame is defined as the emotion that is embedded in the bonds to groups and communities, and therefore a visible physiological reaction—blush- ing—is attached to it. Shame is a tremendously complex emotion, depend- ent on specific contexts, related to a range of other emotions, and actions (Lewis, 2000). Violations of self-esteem, humiliation and stigmatization cause shame as well as anger, varying with the context and the concerns. Obviously, legal procedures have the potential to evoke shame in offenders, but like other modern institutions they do not require particular emotional reactions.11 The return of shame might have counterproductive conse- quences when shame interferes with procedural justice and fairness, and causes anger and defiance. Legal institutions are not based on a small number of basic emotions, but on different and contradictory ones. Processes of punishment are linked to feelings of disgust as well as being embedded in emotions of sympathy. Any efforts to bring one of these to the forefront, and make it the foundation of criminal justice procedures, will necessarily ignore the range of moral sentiments which are involved in the individual as well as in the collective. The fact that emotional reactions are attached to moral norms does not necessarily imply the strategic use of emotions in, for example, defining laws against hate crimes or violations of human rights. The complex and complicated role and space of emotions within the legal system does not allow for easy solutions. Theoretical Criminology 6(3)312 Notes 1. The place of emotions is not assigned exclusively to the criminal court. Tort laws and family courts similarly deal with intense emotions. 2. Research consistently shows that victims mostly want to have their damage restored, and that they are rarely vengeful in their demands for punishment for the offender (Sessar, 1992). Victims seem to be, in particular, sensitive to the impact of legal action within their social networks. 3. See, for revisions of the theory and practice, Ahmed et al. (2001). 4. At the turn of the 18th to the 19th century, public emotions and compas- sion started to be directed towards the offender, in particular those who were imprisoned. The attack on the Bastille during the French Revolution was driven by public outrage about innocent prisoners (though they were actually quite comfortably accommodated); operas like Beethoven’s Fidelio show how public emotions were expressed in the arts. The ‘longue durée’ of compassion with the offender as a victim of society, which lasted through the 19th and 20th century, seems today to have come to a halt. 5. In terms of Elias’ theory of the civilization process, these developments are often analysed as ‘de-civilization’ (Fletcher, 1995, 1997; Pratt, 2000). Nonetheless, this perspective only grasps the regulation or de-regulation of the expression of emotions, and implies a strong bias towards processes of social control. 6. When I asked a movie director why people cry in the cinema, but not in the theatre, his answer was clear and to the point: ‘Close-ups’. 7. See Katz (1999: 316) for a more detailed discussion. 8. See Farrall (2001) for an exploration of ‘anger’ about crime. His results show that ‘anger about crime’ seems to be more an emotional reaction that people feel they ought to have than an actual emotional experience. Jones and Newburn (2002) show that notwithstanding public outrage and support for ‘Sarah’s Law’, its final failure in Britain shows it not to be a solely emotionalized public issue. 9. Ekman and Davidson (1994), and Lewis and Haviland-Jones (2000) provide excellent overviews. 10. Since Browning analysed the files of the investigation and ensuing inter- rogation that took place some 10 years later, these are memories of emotions, which nonetheless seemed to be still extremely vivid at that time. These emotions of disgust were expressed at a time when the moral code had been definitely changed, at least officially and in public. 11. We are not required to feel emotions about our work, or our superiors, or what we produce. Nonetheless, in a recent case in Britain the lack of display of shame and remorse by the offender was the reason explicitly given for a severe sanction. Karstedt—Emotions and criminal justice 313 References Ahmed, Eliza, H. Nathan, J. Braithwaite and V. Braithwaite (2001) Shame Management through Reintegration. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Anderson, Benedict (1983) Imagined Communities. Reflections on the Origins and Spread of Nationalism. London: Verso. Anderson, Digby (ed.) (1995) This Will Hurt. The Restoration of Virtue and Civic Order. London: The Social Affairs Unit. Bandes, Susan A. (1999a) ‘Introduction’, in S. Bandes (ed.) The Passions of Law. New York: New York University Press. Bandes, Susan (ed.) (1999b) The Passions of Law. New York: New York University Press. Barbalet, Jack M. (1998) Emotion, Social Theory and Social Structure. A Macrosociological Approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Boltanski, Luc (1999) Distant Suffering. Morality, Media and Politics. Cam- bridge: Cambridge University Press. Bourgois, Philippe (1995) In Search of Respect. Selling Crack in El Barrio. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Braithwaite, John (1989) Crime, Shame and Reintegration. Cambridge: Cam- bridge University Press. Braithwaite, John (2001) ‘Crime in a Convict Republic’, The Modern Law Review 64(1): 11–50. Browning, Christopher (1992) Ordinary Men: Reserve Police Battalion 101 and the Final Solution in Poland. New York: HarperCollins. Douglas, Mary (1993) ‘Emotion and Culture in Theories of Justice’, Economy and Society 22(4): 501–15. Dunning, E. (1992) ‘“Culture”, “Civilization” and the Sociology of Sport’, Innovation: The European Journal of Social Sciences 5(4): 7–19. Dunning, E., P. Murphy and J. Williams (1986) ‘Spectator Violence at Football Matches: Towards a Sociological Explanation’, British Journal of Sociology 37(2): 221–44. Ekman, Paul and Richard R. Davidson (eds) (1994) The Nature of Emotion. Fundamental Questions. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Elster, Jon (1989) The Cement of Society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Elster, Jon (1999) Alchemies of the Mind. Rationality and Emotions. Cam- bridge: Cambridge University Press. Farrall, Stephen (2001) ‘Anger, Fear and Victimisation: Emotional Responses without Emotions’, paper presented at joint meetings of Law and Society Association and Research Committee on the Sociology of Law (ISA), Central European University, Budapest, July. Fletcher, Jonathan (1995) ‘Towards a Theory of Decivilizing Processes’, Am- sterdams Sociologisch Tijdskrift 22(3): 283–96. Fletcher, Jonathan (1997) Violence and Civilization. An Introduction to the Work of Norbert Elias. Cambridge: Polity. Theoretical Criminology 6(3)314 Freiberg, Arie (2001) ‘Affective Versus Effective Justice. Instrumentalism and Emotionalism in Criminal Justice’, Punishment and Society 3(2): 265–78. Frijda, Nico H. (1994) ‘The Lex Talionis: On Vengeance’, in S. van Goozen, N. van de Poll and J. Sergeant (eds) Emotions: Essays in Emotion Theory, pp. 264–89. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum. Frijda, Nico H. (1996) ‘Passions: Emotion and Socially Consequential Be- havior’, in R. Kavanaugh, B. Zimmerberg and S. Fein (eds) Emotion. Interdisciplinary Perspectives, pp. 1–27. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum. Jones, Trevor and Tim Newburn (2002) ‘Policy Convergence and Crime Control in the USA and UK: “Streams” of Influence and “Levels” of Impact’, Criminal Justice 2(2). Kahan, Dan M. (1999) ‘The Progressive Appropriation of Disgust’, in S. Bandes (ed.) The Passions of Law, pp. 63–79. New York: New York University Press. Karstedt, Susanne (1989) ‘Sanktionserfahrungen und Sanktionserwartungen von Jugendlichen. Eine Empirische Studie zur Integration von Individual- und Generalpraevention’, in Bundesministerium der Justiz (ed.) Jugend- rechtsreform durch die Praxis, pp. 168–96. Bonn: Bundesministerium der Justiz. Karstedt, Susanne (1993) Webs of Significance, Nets of Control. Experiences and Expectations of Sanctions by Juveniles. Bielefeld: University of Biele- feld. Karstedt, Susanne (1996) ‘Recht und Scham’, Neue Kriminalpolitik 8(4): 22–5. Karstedt, Susanne (2000) ‘Review: Distant Suffering. Morality, Media and Politics’, The Sociological Review 48(4): 670–2. Karstedt, Susanne (2001) ‘Die moralische Staerke schwacher Bindungen: In- dividualismus und Gewalt im Kulturvergleich’, Monatsschrift fuer Krimino- logie und Strafrechtsreform 84(3): 226–43. Katz, Jack (1999) How Emotions Work. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Laster, Kathy and Pat O’Malley (1996) ‘Sensitive New-Age Laws: The Reasser- tion of Emotionality in Law’, International Journal of the Sociology of Law 24(1): 21–40. Lewis, Michael (2000) ‘Self-Conscious Emotions: Embarrassement, Pride, Shame and Guilt’, in M. Lewis and Jeanette M. Haviland-Jones (eds) Handbook of Emotions, 2nd edn, pp. 623–36. New York: Guilford Press. Lewis, Michael and Jeanette M. Haviland-Jones (eds) (2000) Handbook of Emotions, 2nd edn. New York: Guilford Press. Luther, Martin (undated) Die 95 Thesen Martin Luthers. Wittenberg: Horst Bargmann Verlag fuer Kunst und Touristik. Massaro, Toni M. (1991) ‘Shame, Culture, and American Criminal Law’, Michigan Law Review 89(6): 1880–944. Massaro, Toni M. (1997) ‘The Meanings of Shame’, Psychology, Public Policy, and Law 3(4): 645–704. Karstedt—Emotions and criminal justice 315 Mesquita, Batja, Nico H. Frijda and Klaus R. Scherer (1997) ‘Culture and Emotion’, in J.W. Berry, P.R. Dasen and T.S. Saraswathi (eds) Basic Processes and Human Development. Handbook of Cross-Cultural Psychology, vol. 2, pp. 255–97. Boston, MA: Allyn & Bacon. Mikula, Gerold, Klaus R. Scherer and Ursula Athenstaedt (1998) ‘The Role of Injustice in the Elicitation of Differential Emotional Reactions’, Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 24(7): 769–83. Neckel, Sighard (1999) ‘Blanker Neid, Blinde Wut. Sozialstruktur und Kollek- tive Gefuehle’, Leviathan 27(2): 146–65. Newsweek (1995) ‘The Return of Shame’, 6 February. Nunner-Winkler, Gertrud (1998) ‘Empathie, Scham und Schuld: Zur Mor- alischen Bedeutung von Emotionen’, in M. Grundmann (ed.) Konstruktivis- tische Sozialisationsforschung: Ansaetze und Methodische Ueberlegungen zu einer Konstruktivistischen Theorie der Sozialisation, pp. 118–43. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. Nussbaum, Martha C. (1999) ‘“Secret Sewers of Vice”: Disgust, Bodies and the Law’, in S. Bandes (ed.) The Passions of Law, pp. 19–62. New York: New York University Press. Plato (1987) Protagoras. Greek/German, translated and commented by H.-W. Krautz. Stuttgart: Philipp Reclam jun. Poletta, Francesca (2001) ‘The Laws of Passion. Reviewing Bandes’s The Passions of Law’, Law and Society Review 35(2): 467–94. Posner, Richard A. (1999) ‘Emotion Versus Emotionalism in Law’, in S. Bandes (ed.) The Passions of Law, pp. 309–29. New York: New York University Press. Posner, Richard A. (2000) Law and the Emotions. John M. Olin Law and Economics Working Paper No. 103. Chicago, IL: The Law School, Uni- versity of Chicago. Pratt, John (2000) ‘Emotive and Ostentatious Punishment: Its Decline and Resurgence in Modern Society’, Punishment and Society 2(4): 417–41. Scherer, Klaus (1991) ‘Die Emotionalen Grundlagen des Gerechtigkeitsge- fuehls’, in D. Frey and G. Koehnken (eds) Bericht ueber den 37. Kongress der Deutschen Gesellschaft fuer Psychologie in Kiel 1990, pp. 411–20. Goettin- gen: Hogrefe. Scherer, Klaus (1997) ‘The Role of Culture in Emotion-Antecedent Appraisal’, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 73(4): 902–22. Schwartz, Shalom H. (1992) ‘Universals in the Content and Structure of Values: Theoretical Advances and Empirical Tests in 20 Countries’, in M.P. Zanna (ed.) Advances in Experimental Psychology, vol. 25, pp. 1–65. Orlando, FL: Academic Press. Schwartz, Shalom H. (1994) ‘Are There Universals in the Structure and Contents of Human Values?’, Journal of Social Issues 50(4): 19–45. Schwartz, Shalom H. and Lilach Sagiv (1995) ‘Identifying Culture-Specifics in the Content and Structure of Values’, Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology 26(1): 92–116. Theoretical Criminology 6(3)316 Sessar, Klaus (1992) Widergutmachen oder Strafen. Einstellungen in der Bev- oelkerung und der Justiz. Pfaffenweiler: Centaurus. Skillen, A.J. (1980) ‘How to Say Things with Walls’, Philosophy 55(5): 509–23. Solomon, Robert C. (1990) A Passion for Justice. Emotions and the Origins of the Social Contract. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley. Solomon, Robert C. (1994) ‘Sympathy and Vengeance: The Role of the Emotions in Justice’, in S. van Goozen, N. van de Poll and J. Sergeant (eds) Emotions: Essays in Emotion Theory, pp. 291–311. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum. Taylor, Charles (1992) Multiculturalism and ‘the Politics of Recognition’. An Essay. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Taylor, Gabriele (1987) Pride, Shame, and Guilt. Oxford: Clarendon. Triandis, Harry C. (1994) ‘Major Cultural Syndromes and Emotions’, in S. Kitayama and H.R. Markus (eds) Emotion and Culture. Empirical Studies of Mutual Influence, pp. 285–306. Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. Tyler, Tom R. (1990) Why People Obey the Law. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Vester, Heinz-Guenter (1991) Emotion, Gesellschaft und Kultur. Grundzuege einer Soziologischen Theorie der Emotionen. Opladen: Westdeutscher Ver- lag. Williams, Simon J. (2001) Emotion and Social Theory. Corporeal Reflections on the (Ir)Rational. London: Sage. Wouters, Cas (1986) ‘Formalization and Informalization: Changing Tension Balances in Civilizing Processes’, Theory, Culture and Society 3(2): 1–18. SUSANNE KARSTEDT is Professor of Criminology in the Department of Criminology, Keele University, UK. She has researched and published on cross-cultural criminology, in particular violence and corruption, elite criminality, social capital and violence and transitional justice. She is presently directing a comparative research project on the moral economy of modern market societies, funded by the Volkswagen Foundation. Karstedt—Emotions and criminal justice 317 work_63s7cw7mnfhhrgwgjsxh6irhri ---- PowerPoint-Präsentation Using Factorial Surveys to Study Justice Perceptions: Five Methodological Problems of Attitudinal Justice Research SFB 882 Working Paper Series ○ No. 47 ○ January 2015 DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities http://www.sfb882.uni-bielefeld.de/ Stefan Liebig Carsten Sauer Stefan Friedhoff Stefan Liebig, Carsten Sauer and Stefan Friedhoff Using Factorial Surveys to Study Justice Perceptions: Five Methodological Problems of Attitudinal Justice Research SFB 882 Working Paper Series, No. 47 DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities Research Project A6 Bielefeld, January 2015 SFB 882 Working Paper Series General Editors: Martin Diewald, Thomas Faist and Stefan Liebig ISSN 2193-9624 This publication has been funded by the German Research Foundation (DFG). SFB 882 Working Papers are refereed scholarly papers. Submissions are reviewed by peers in a two-stage SFB 882 internal and external refereeing process before a final decision on publication is made. The Working Paper Series is a forum for presenting works in progress. Readers should communicate comments on the manuscript directly to the author(s). The papers can be downloaded from the SFB 882 website http://www.sfb882.uni-bielefeld.de/ SFB 882 “From Heterogeneities to Inequalities” University of Bielefeld Faculty of Sociology PO Box 100131 D-33501 Bielefeld Germany Phone: +49-(0)521-106-4942 or +49-(0)521-106-4613 Email: office.sfb882@uni-bielefeld.de Web: http://www.sfb882.uni-bielefeld.de/ DFG Research Center (SFB) “From Heterogeneities to Inequalities” Whether fat or thin, male or female, young or old – people are different. Alongside their physi- cal features, they also differ in terms of nationality and ethnicity; in their cultural preferences, lifestyles, attitudes, orientations, and philosophies; in their competencies, qualifications, and traits; and in their professions. But how do such heterogeneities lead to social inequalities? What are the social mechanisms that underlie this process? These are the questions pursued by the DFG Research Center (Sonderforschungsbereich (SFB)) “From Heterogeneities to Inequalities” at Bielefeld University, which was approved by the German Research Foundation (DFG) as “SFB 882” on May 25, 2011. In the social sciences, research on inequality is dispersed across different research fields such as education, the labor market, equality, migration, health, or gender. One goal of the SFB is to integrate these fields, searching for common mechanisms in the emergence of inequality that can be compiled into a typology. More than fifty senior and junior researchers and the Bielefeld University Library are involved in the SFB. Along with sociologists, it brings together scholars from the Bielefeld University faculties of Business Administration and Economics, Educational Science, Health Science, and Law, as well as from the German Institute for Economic Research (DIW) in Berlin and the University of Erlangen-Nuremberg. In addition to carrying out research, the SFB is concerned to nurture new academic talent, and therefore provides doctoral training in its own integrated Research Training Group. A data infrastructure project has also been launched to archive, prepare, and disseminate the data gathered. Research Project A6 “The Legitimation of Inequalities – Structural Conditions of Justice Attitudes over the Life-span” This project investigates (a) the conditions under which inequalities are perceived as problems of justice and (b) how embedment in different social contexts influences the formation of attitudes to justice across the life course. We assume that individuals evaluate inequalities in terms of whether they consider them just, and that they hold particular attitudes toward justice because, and as long as, these help them to attain their fundamental goals and to solve, especially, the problems that arise through cooperation with other people (cooperative relations). As a result, attitudes on justice are not viewed either as rigidly stable orientations across the life span or as “Sunday best beliefs” i.e. short-lived opinions that are adjusted continuously to fit situational interests. Instead, they are regarded as being shaped by the opportunities for learning and making comparisons in different phases of the life course and different social contexts. The goal of the project is to use longitudinal survey data to explain why individuals have particular notions of justice. The key aspect is taken to be changes in the social context – particularly households, social networks, or workplaces – in which individuals are embedded across their life course. This is because social contexts offer opportunities to make social comparisons and engage in social learning, processes that are decisive in the formation of particular attitudes to justice. The project will test this empirically by setting up a special longitudinal panel in which the same individuals will be interviewed three times over an 11- year period. The results of the project will permit conclusions to be drawn on the consequences of changes in a society's social and economic structure for its members' ideas about justice. The project therefore supplements the analysis of the mechanisms that produce inequality, which is the focus of SFB 882 as a whole, by looking at subjective evaluations, and it complements that focus by addressing the mechanisms of attitude formation. Research goals (1) Analysis of the conditions in which justice is used as a criterion for evaluating inequalities. (2) Explanation of attitudes toward justice as the outcome of comparison and learning processes mediated by the social context. (3) Longitudinal observation of the individual development of attitudes to justice over the life course. Research design (1) Continuation and expansion of the longitudinal survey of evaluations of justice conducted by the German Socio-Economic Panel Study (SOEP). (2) Commencement of an independent longitudinal panel with ties to the process-generated individual data of the German Institute for Employment Research (IAB) and information on companies and households (the plan is to carry out three survey waves over an 11-year period). The Authors Stefan Liebig is Professor of Sociology with a special focus on Social Inequality and Social Stratification at the Faculty of Sociology, Bielefeld University, and Principal Investigator of the Collaborative Research Centre (SFB) 882 research project A6, “The Legitimation of Inequalities – Structural Conditions of Justice Attitudes over the Life-span”. His research interests are empirical justice research, organizations and social inequality, and methods of empirical research. Recent publications are “The justice of earnings in dual-earner households”, in: Research in Social Stratification and Mobility 30 (2012): 219-232 (with C. Sauer and J. Schupp); “Gerechtigkeit”, in: S. Mau & N. M. Schöneck (Eds.), Handwörterbuch zur Gesellschaft Deutschlands (2013), Springer VS: 286-299 (with C. Sauer and P. Valet); “The Application of Factorial Surveys in General Population Samples: The Effects of Respondent Age and Education on Response Times and Response Consistency”, in: Survey Research Methods 5 (2011): 89-102 (with C. Sauer, K. Auspurg and T. Hinz). Contact: stefan.liebig@uni-bielefeld.de Carsten Sauer is a postdoctoral research fellow in the SFB 882, project A6 at Bielefeld University. His research interests include the explanation of behavior, social inequality and justice and quantitative research methods (especially factorial surveys). Among his recent publications are: “The Factorial Survey as a Method for Measuring Sensitive Issues”, in: U. Engel, B. Jann, P. Lynn, A. Scherpenzeel, P. Sturgis, (Eds.), Improving Survey Methods. Lessons from recent Research (2014), Routledge: 137-149 (with K. Auspurg, T. Hinz, S. Liebig); “Incentives and Inhibitors of Abusing Academic Positions: Analysing University Students' Decisions about Bribing Academic Staff”, in: European Sociological Review 30 (2014): 230-241 (with P. Graeff, S. Satter, G. Mehlkop); “Less is Sometimes More: Consequences of Overpayment on Job Satisfaction and Absenteeism”, in: Social Justice Research 26 (2013): 132-150 (with P. Valet); “When Decisions Should Be Shared: A Study of Social Norms in Medical Decision Making Using a Factorial Survey Approach”, in: Medical Decision Making 33 (2013): 37-47 (with M. Müller-Engelmann et al.). Contact: carsten.sauer@uni-bielefeld.de Stefan Friedhoff is a member of the SFB 882 project “Information and Data Infrastructure” (INF) and PhD candidate at the Bielefeld Graduate School in History and Sociology (BGHS). In the INF project he assists researchers with problems of everyday documentation and improves documentation practices. His research interests focus on data management, survey methodology, social inequalities and factorial survey research. Contact: stefan.friedhoff@uni-bielefeld.de Using Factorial Surveys to Study Justice Perceptions: Five Methodological Problems of Attitudinal Justice Research Stefan Liebig, Carsten Sauer, and Stefan Friedhoff1 Summary: This article provides an overview of how factorial surveys have been used in justice research in the past. It addresses the question of why this method is particularly useful to survey attitudes toward justice. This question is discussed with reference to five problems of empirical justice research. For each of these problems, findings are presented from recent justice research that has used the factorial survey method, with a focus on assessing the allocation and distribution of goods (earnings/income, transfer payments, pensions) and burdens (taxes). The paper concludes with a discussion of future developments and possible applications in this research field. Introduction For a long time, the question of what is just and what is not was regarded as a purely normative problem and, thus, as a subject of philosophy, legal theory, or theology. The aim of this normative justice research is to provide answers to Kant’s question “What ought I to do?”, and to do so has to identify principles or rules of justice that ensure that, from a moral point of view, the allocation and distribution of goods and burdens can be regarded as just (e.g., Rawls, 1975). Starting around the middle of the last century, a descriptive, or empirical, line of research on justice began to establish itself, first in psychology, and later in the social sciences and in economics (Adams, 1965; Deutsch, 1985; Jasso, 1978; Runciman, 1966; Törnblom, 1992). This steadily growing line of research examines what individuals and societies consider to be a just distribution of goods and burdens; why a state of justice is regarded as something worth achieving; and what consequences can be observed in a society when something is perceived as just or injust. Most of this empirical research has focused on the study of attitudes toward procedural and distributive justice (cf. Liebig & Sauer, 2013, 2015). While questions of procedural justice involve an evaluation of decision-making processes regarding the allocation and distribution of goods or burdens (Deutsch, 1985; Jasso, 1980; Törnblom, 1992; Wegener, 1987), questions of distributive justice involve an evaluation of the outcomes of such processes. The main finding of this research is that attitudes toward or beliefs about justice, as well as evaluations of concrete outcomes, not only depend on individual characteristics—and thus do not have the status of personal traits—but are affected by the social situation in which an individual is embedded and the type of resource that is allocated. A specific allocation amount can therefore only be assessed on the basis of contextual information (Hegtvedt, 2006). This is why judgments concerning distributive justice are always complex, context- dependent, and context-related attitudes. At least five methodological problems result from this complexity which are partially known from other areas of attitude research but are particularly important in justice research. First, the high degree of context dependency of judgments implies that a lack of contextualization can lead to systematically biased measurements of attitudes toward justice, particularly in survey-based justice research, but also in experimental behavioral economics, where researchers deduce individual attitudes toward justice from behavior in very abstract and artificial distribution situations. Second, since attitudes toward justice appear to be determined by a variety of very different factors, the actual importance and, especially, the relative importance of these factors must be determined (for example, to draw conclusions about their role in the generation of distributive injustices). This leads 1 This paper is an outcome of the research project “The Legitimation of Inequalities – Structural Conditions of Justice Attitudes over the Lifespan,” which is funded by the German Research Foundation (DFG) within the Collaborative Research Center 882 “From Heterogeneities to Inequalities” at Bielefeld University, Germany. 1 us to a third problem: in order to investigate the causes and influencing factors of individual perceptions of justice, in some fields of justice research, experimental studies are conducted in the laboratory, with only a certain group of individuals—usually students—participating (Henrich et al., 2010). As a result, the findings are often based on the study of convenience samples which include students and in which the external validity is usually not sufficiently clarified. This is particularly problematic in justice research because there is evidence that individual attitudes toward justice are influenced by sociostructural position and previous individual experiences, among other things. The fourth problem, the problem of social-desirability bias in response behavior (Paulhus, 1984), is particularly important when measuring attitudes toward justice because attitudes are sometimes not measured appropriately, so that the findings obtained lead to erroneous conclusions. The fifth problem is the problem of measuring and identifying causal relationships; this problem is particularly relevant when conducting research on the causes of certain attitudes, whether toward justice or other factors. In this article, we will show how factorial surveys can be used, if not to overcome, then at least to reduce, the risk and impact of these five problems in empirical research on justice. We will review studies that analyze attitudes toward distributive justice and report problems in relation to the illustrated key results.2 The article concludes with a discussion of future developments and possible applications. Factorial Surveys in Empirical Justice Research Factorial surveys have been used in empirical justice research for over 30 years to determine what ideas exist about the fair allocation of goods or burdens (e.g., Beck & Opp, 2001; Jasso, 2006; Rossi & Anderson, 1982; Wallander, 2009). Generally speaking, respondents in these studies are asked to evaluate short descriptions (“vignettes”) of recipients (e.g., employees, households), in which the individual or situational characteristics (“dimensions”) used to describe the case are varied systematically in their levels. Since these levels are simultaneously changed among vignettes, the procedure is also referred to as “multifactorial.” Figure 1 shows a vignette that is used to measure attitudes toward the distributive justice of income. The description consists of five dimensions, four of which are characteristics describing the individual (age, gender, vocational training, occupation), with the fifth dimension indicating the individual’s gross earnings. The specific values of these characteristics are varied from vignette to vignette. Respondents are then asked to rate the justice of the gross earnings presented on an 11-point scale. In the analysis, these ratings are treated as dependent variables, and the five dimensions are treated as independent variables. By systematically varying these dimensions, their importance for justice evaluations can be estimated through statistical analysis and conclusions about justice can be drawn, with questions that can be addressed in this way including: Should earnings increase with age? Should women receive the same income as men? Should individuals with vocational training earn more than individuals without training? 2 The following illustration is based on a literature review that involved two steps. The first step was to search for articles in Google Scholar and the Social Science Citation Index which use any combination of the German and English keywords “justice” or “fairness” [“Gerechtigkeit”] and “factorial survey” [“faktorieller Survey”] or “vignette(s)” [“Vignette(n)”]. Following the procedure described by Wallander (2009), the results were then complemented by publications citing the article “Who Should Get What? Fairness Judgments of the Distribution of Earnings” by Alves and Rossi (1978), because it is one of the first and most frequently cited articles in justice research that use factorial surveys. 19 articles in German and English were identified in this way. An overview of the studies used here can be found in the Appendix. 2 Figure 1. Example vignette with five dimensions A 60-year-old woman with occupational training works as a social-worker. Her gross monthly earnings are €2,500 (before taxes and transfers). In your opinion, are her monthly gross earnings just, unjustly high, or unjustly low? Unjustly low Just Unjustly high -5 -4 -3 -2 -1 0 +1 +2 +3 +4 +5            Source: Sauer et al. (2011) In the past, factorial surveys have been used in justice research primarily to examine attitudes toward the allocation of monetary rewards (individual earnings, household income, welfare-state transfer payments) or burdens (taxes). Compared with the use of vignettes in other fields of research (e.g., Wallander, 2009), the proportion of factorial surveys used in population surveys is larger in justice research, and there are also more international comparative studies (Auspurg et al., 2013; Hysom & Fişek, 2011; Jasso & Meyersson Milgrom, 2008; Schrenker, 2009). Recent applications of factorial surveys in justice research show two methodological peculiarities. (1) As regards the decisive advantage of factorial surveys, which is to provide the respondents with contextualizing information, studies differ in the number of dimensions (information content) and vignettes per respondent. The numbers of dimensions used per vignette range from three (Jann, 2008) to ten (Auspurg et al., 2013; Gatskova, 2013; Sauer et al., 2009). The number of vignettes to be evaluated varies much more. This is due to a methodological peculiarity. Especially in the early days of using factorial surveys, a very large number of vignettes were presented; the studies of Jasso, Rossi, and their colleagues used between 40 and 60 vignettes per respondent (Alves & Rossi, 1978; Jasso, 1994; Jasso & Meyersson Milgrom, 2008; Jasso & Rossi, 1977; Jasso & Webster, 1997). They did so because they wanted to obtain as many data points as possible for each subject to improve the estimation of individual judgment behavior (within-analysis) and to make comparisons among respondents based on their judgments (between-analysis). This procedure involves a two-step process. In the first step, individual regressions are estimated to measure the influence of the dimensions on the justice judgments of a single respondent (within-estimation). In the second step, these coefficients are used as individual traits to analyze correlations or differences among groups of respondents or other attitude measurements (between-estimation). (2) The second methodological peculiarity has to do with the use of open and magnitude response scales, which are used to avoid direct measurement. When asked the direct question, respondents state what they think would be a just reward the individual described in the vignette should receive (Hysom & Fişek, 2011; Shepelak & Alwin, 1986). When the respondents are asked the indirect question, the justice evaluation (amount of injustice) is measured, but the respondents are not asked to specify the reward (e.g., earnings). The actual amount is determined ex-post using a two-step estimation procedure. A classic application is the determination of the just amount of earnings (for details, see Jasso, 2006; Jasso & Meyersson Milgrom, 2008; Jasso & Wegener, 1997). This procedure is based on the theory of Jasso (1978, 2006), according to which the justice evaluation J is the product of the logarithmic ratio of the actual earnings (A) and the just earnings (C), as well as an individual constant (θ) (Jiv = θi × ln (Av / Civ), with i = judging individual and v = vignette). Both 3 C and θ are unknown and must be estimated. To calculate the just reward C, it is necessary to transform Jasso’s equation (Civ = Av × exp (–Jiv / θi)) and estimate θ as the slope coefficient of individual regression equations.3 The estimation is done by regressing individual-specific bivariate regressions of all judgments of an individual (J) on the actual earnings given in the vignettes. The estimated slope coefficient then provides the individual constant θ, which is used to calculate the just earnings for each vignette. This procedure makes it possible to express the attitudes toward justice in the reward units (see Figure 2). It is obvious that in this procedure at least an interval scale level of the justice judgment J is needed. For this reason in particular, open scales or magnitude scales are used (Jasso & Meyersson Milgrom, 2008; Jasso & Webster, 1999; Liebig & Mau, 2002, 2005) in addition to conventional 9- or 11-point rating scales (Alves & Rossi, 1978; Jasso, 1994; Jasso & Rossi, 1977; Jasso & Webster, 1997; Schrenker, 2009).4 The rationale for using these indirect measures of attitudes toward justice is that certain groups of respondents might find it too difficult to state specific rewards or burdens. More important, respondents do not express their own perceptions when asked about just rewards, because they are too heavily influenced by the given rewards (Jasso, 2006; for arguments to the contrary, see Markovsky & Eriksson, 2012). However, this method has been critically discussed (Auspurg & Hinz 2015), and the use of open or magnitude scales has been considered to be particularly problematic (Sauer et al., 2009, 2014). But how might factorial surveys be used to reduce the methodological problems of empirical research on justice? In the following, we will provide a detailed description of the five problems mentioned and explain how factorial surveys might be used to reduce these problems in justice research. Issues of Empirical Justice Research and Findings from Studies Involving Factorial Surveys Contextual Information: Complexity of Distribution Processes The first problem of analytical justice attitude research is rooted in the very subject itself. In most cases, the question of whether or not the allocation of certain rewards or burdens is just can be answered only on the basis of contextual information (Hegtvedt, 2006). This is because the actual allocation of rewards and burdens itself depends on a combination of individual and structural characteristics. The amount of actual earnings is determined by various factors, including individual performance, human capital, age, gender, occupation, industrial sector, and company size. The questions that arise when the justice of earnings is assessed are which of these factors the respondents think determine the amount of fair earnings and what relative importance each dimension has. Previous research shows that individuals judge allocation and distribution results on the basis of very general rules or principles of distribution, which also specify which dimensions the respondents will consider to what extent. The most important principles besides the principle of equality are the proportionality or equity principle (rewards should be proportional to an individual’s current expenses and efforts), the principle of need (individual requirements in terms of minimum social standards and non-self-inflicted disadvantages should be considered in the allocation), and the principle of entitlement (an individual’s position and status in the hierarchical structure of a society or a group should be taken into consideration) (Liebig & Sauer, 2013, 2015). The respondents’ decision as to which of these principles should guide the allocation or distribution process depends on the situation and on the type of goods or burdens to be distributed (e.g., income, 3 The equation is solved using the following conversion and Slutsky’s theorem: J = θ × ln A – θ × ln C = a + θ × ln A (cf. Jasso, 2007; Jasso & Wegener, 1997). 4 When the magnitude scale is used, respondents are asked to express the degree of their feeling of injustice by giving a random number or by drawing a line. To ensure the comparability of judgments, the respondents are first presented with a vignette (anchor vignette), which is similar for all respondents. 4 medical assistance). In making such decisions, respondents might also use a combination of any of these principles. It is important to note that there is no way any of these principles could be “simply” applied, because it is impossible to make generalized statements about what “individual performance” actually is, which of the criteria required are legitimate, or which status characteristics of an individual should be rewarded and with what amounts. This more precise determination of the conditions and their links to specific reward amounts in turn depends on the context, and is the result, of social-comparison processes. Only by comparing themselves with other individuals or groups (individual reference individuals or “generalized others”) can respondents develop concrete ideas about what might constitute a just reward or burden. Thus, information on the recipients and the situational conditions is needed to decide which principles of justice should apply in a given case and what reward or burden is just or unjust. Survey-based justice research in particular relies primarily on item-based measurement instruments, which provide respondents with little contextual information and measure attitudes toward justice on a very general and abstract level.5 The aim of these measurements is to identify cross-context preferences or general normative orientations.6 Item-based measurements are useful, generally speaking, but can also lead to a systematic distortion of response behavior. Since item-based instruments are designed to evoke a response behavior that favors equal distributions of goods and burdens, their exclusive use could lead to an overestimation of equality preferences. Studies on empirical justice research show that respondents always rely on “equality heuristics” if there is too little information about distributive decisions. A similar behavior is observed when the respondents want to or can invest only little cognitive capacity in processing the instruments used because the instruments are too abstract, too difficult to comprehend, or not concise enough (Keller et al., 2013; Messick, 1993; Roch et al., 2000). The use of the equality principle can be understood as a “rule of thumb or an intuitive rule of sharing” (Keller et al., 2013, p. 172) and as what might be called the “default” attitude in resolving allocation and distribution conflicts in “ambiguous, novel, or complex social situations” (Messick, 1993, p. 28). The advantage is that when using the equality principle, no information is needed about the recipients of the allocation or distribution or about any other situational parameters. Nor are there any complex cognitive processes required of the respondents to be able to make a more differentiated allocation and distribution (Messick, 1993). By exclusively using item-based questions it is possible to favor this use of a simple equality-oriented heuristic. Factorial surveys allow researchers to avoid this problem. The first reason is that it requires respondents to make greater cognitive efforts than do item-based attitude measurements (Sauer et al., 2009, 2011). The vignettes presented have a more complex structure (several dimensions), and in most cases respondents are asked to evaluate several vignettes. Second, in a factorial survey respondents are provided with more information. The contexts of the evaluation can be compared in a way that is more appropriate to the subject; for example, when asked to evaluate the justice of earnings, individual factors such as performance and job experience may be complemented with contextual dimensions such as the economic situation of the company or the situation of the family (Sauer et al., 2009, 2011). In addition, it is likely that the use of realistic vignettes helps the respondents to imagine the situation better and thus enables them to make appropriate decisions that go beyond simple heuristics. For the measurement of income inequality this means that measurements that use factorial surveys should show significantly lower “inequality aversion” compared with classic item-based questions. This is suggested by the results of a population survey conducted in Germany in 2009 (Sauer et al., 2011). Of the 1,600 respondents recruited for an item- 5 Experimental behavioral economics operates in a similar way when distribution behavior in highly artificial game situations is used to draw conclusions about the justice preferences of participants, most of whom are students (cf. Fehr & Schmidt, 2006). 6 One example is an item respondents in the German General Social Survey (ALLBUS) are asked about on a regular basis to determine whether they agree with the statement “Income inequality in Germany is too high” (ALLBUS 2010, Item 6a), in order to draw conclusions about preferences of income inequalities in society. 5 based measurement, 91 percent stated that income inequality in Germany was “too high” or “far too high.” From these responses a clear equality preference can be derived. The same questionnaire also asked respondents to evaluate the justice of earnings of vignette persons. As Figure 2 shows, respondents clearly differentiated between just earnings depending on the occupation of the vignette individuals (Sauer et al., 2009), thus creating inequality with their judgments. Figure 2. Earnings rated as just and actual earnings by occupation of vignette individuals in Germany in 2009 Source: Attitudes toward justice from Sauer et al. (2009), actual earnings by occupation (mean of full-time-employed in a given occupation), calculated on the basis of SOEP 2009 The triangles connected by the continuous line in Figure 2 show the just earnings for each of the ten occupations (mean values), which were estimated on the basis of the respondents’ judgments, while the squares connected by the dashed line show the actual earnings of each of the occupations as given in the data set of the German Socio-Economic Panel 2009 (averages of full-time employees in each occupation [ISCO four-digit code]). The two lines run fairly parallel, which suggests that the respondents’ judgments were not arbitrary and that the estimations of just earnings based on the justice judgments provide meaningful values. On the whole, the respondents would slightly increase the earnings of individuals in lower-status occupations (manufacturing laborers, hairdressers) and lower the earnings of high-status occupations (medical doctors). However, the existing variation of earnings across occupations is still considered to be just. A uniform distribution of earnings—as could be derived as favored based on the item-based measurement—is not considered to be just. In addition, there is no statistically significant correlation between the inequality preference expressed in the vignette judgments and the preference for smaller inequalities in the item-based measurement. This means that if more detailed information about the potential recipients and their situation is available, the assessment of what constitutes just earnings is more differentiated, and that if this and other contextual information is not available, respondents use the “rule of thumb” 0 1000 2000 3000 4000 5000 6000 7000 8000 Just gross earnings Actual gross earnings 6 appropriate to the given situation and regard greater equality as just. This pattern is consistent with the findings on the use of the “equality heuristics” (see Messick, 1993; Roch et al., 2000). The potential of this method to allow for differentiated judgments of justice by using appropriate “contextualizations” has also been shown by two studies that do not focus explicitly on earnings. The first of these studies, Schaffer (1990), examined what criteria respondents used to determine what they thought would be fair child support payments the parent not living in the same household as their child should make. The results clearly showed a tendency toward justice judgments based on actual needs, with respondents stating that child support payments should be proportional to the income of the persons liable for child support. In other words, the higher the income of the parent liable for child support, the higher the child support payment should be to be considered just. The second study, Liebig and Mau (2002), focused on minimum social security and examined the attitudes toward a minimum income provided by the state. Their finding was that the respondents were generally in favor of a minimum level of social security that would ensure the recipients’ existence, which is consistent with the results of item-based measurements. However, their results also show that respondents think that the actual amount of welfare benefits should depend on whether the individuals described in the vignettes had put themselves in a state of welfare dependency. The general consensus what that those who are in financial distress through their own fault should receive less welfare state support than those who were in financial distress through no fault of their own. Thus, the preference for a uniform distribution is lower if additional information is provided on the potential recipients of an allocation. The above discussion suggests that factorial surveys are more useful in measuring attitudes toward justice that are not the result of routinized behavior in the form of applying an equality heuristic. Relative Importance: The Different Relevance of Individual Allocation Criteria The allocation criteria that underlie factual distribution processes often have different and, more important, competing normative implications. Normative conflicts therefore arise only as a result of the relative weighting of individual criteria, such as when considering the question of whether individuals’ formal education should be given more weight in determining their income than their seniority, their experience, or their actual job performance. Traditional item-based survey methods cannot clearly distinguish between individual determinants. Factorial surveys can make this distinction because the multifactorial design requires respondents to make “trade-offs” among various different dimensions and thus to weigh up individual characteristics against one another. This makes it possible to determine the influence of each named and varied attribute on the respondents’ response or judgment, as well as the relative importance of individual vignette dimensions. This may be done by considering standardized coefficients (Shepelak & Alwin, 1986) or by decomposing into the respective semi-partial explanation of variance (cf. Auspurg et al., 2013; Auspurg & Jäckle, 2012; Gatskova, 2013). Most of the existing research has investigated the relative importance of individual allocation criteria for individual incomes and household incomes, with a focus on two central questions. The first question is: Which of the individual characteristics of the income earners described in the vignettes and which of the situational factors are relevant for the justice evaluation? Here, the individual and situational characteristics are regarded as indicators of the general principles of justice described. The other central question is: Is it possible to identify differences among societies or among social groups? Generally speaking, the results of this research show that respondents actually weigh up several individual and situational factors against one another, and that they give the greatest relative weight to vignette dimensions that are directly related to employment (e.g., 7 Auspurg et al., 2013).7 Key factors in the decision making include occupation, human capital (education and experience), and individual performance: respondents believe that it would be just if the vignette individuals in more prestigious occupations who have more experience, a higher level of education, and above-average performance in the workplace earned more than others (Sauer et al., 2009). Thus, two distribution principles dominate in justice evaluations of earnings: first, the principle of proportionality as described in equity theory (Adams, 1965), because individual performance is seen as a central reward principle. Justice of earnings is constituted not by absolute equality but by proportional equality, that is, by the principle of equal pay for equal performance and unequal pay for unequal performance. Thus, contrary to the findings obtained by using the theoretical models advocated in behavioral economics (Fehr & Schmidt, 2006), individuals do not show “inequality aversion” when it comes to earnings; rather, it would be more accurate to say that they show “inequity aversion,” meaning that injustice is experienced, and is to be avoided, when individuals who have equal expenses achieve unequal outcomes or when individuals achieve equal outcomes with unequal expenses.8 However, because similar weight is given to the allocation category “occupation,” or prestige of the occupation, it is expected that for earnings to be considered just, they must also reflect differences in status. The results for Germany are shown in Figure 2; respondents make a clear differentiation of earnings by occupation (with factors such as level of education, performance, and experience used as control variables). A key observation in this respect is that respondents clearly expect that individuals in occupations with a higher social status and greater prestige should be entitled to a higher income, regardless of their current expenses and benefits.9 Thus, respondents believe that the allocation of income should be based on the principle of entitlement as well as on the proportionality principle. This finding is consistent with the results of a study Hermkens and Boerman (1989) conducted in the Netherlands which found that occupational prestige is the most important determinant for the level of just household income. 7 To compare the weight of individual dimensions in order to determine their relative weight, beta-coefficients (Alves & Rossi, 1978; Hermkens & Boerman, 1989), semi-partial explained variance (Auspurg et al., 2013; Gatskova, 2013), and t-values are considered (Liebig et al., 2010). 8 Incidentally, this inequity aversion has also been observed in non-human primates (see Brosnan, 2006). 9 The term “education” does not allow for a clear distinction because it can be understood not only as an indicator of individual productivity (proportionality principle) but also as a status characteristic (principle of entitlement). 8 Figure 3. A comparison of the relative importance of dimensions in vignette-based and item-based measurements Source: Liebig et al. (2010). The relative weight of the dimensions was measured using t-values. The fact that the studies considered here found that “status criteria” play an equally important role in the just allocation of income as “performance criteria” certainly also has to do with the differentiated form of the attitude measurement used in factorial surveys. If we compare the ranking of the different income criteria obtained directly using item-based survey with the ranking obtained indirectly using a factorial survey, the survey conducted in Germany in 2009 reveals significant differences. While the item-based survey leads to the conclusion that the proportionality principle is the most important criterion, factorial surveys show that the principle of entitlement (occupation) is the most important principle. The results also indicate that individual need is another important allocation criterion besides the two central principles of proportionality and entitlement: the number of children to be supported or marital status also constitute legitimate claims. Respondents think that individuals should be allocated a higher income if they have more family responsibilities, if they are the sole breadwinner, or if they have to support children. The above clearly shows that the evaluation of earnings is based on a combination and weighting of different principles of justice. This was the key assumption of the model proposed by Leventhal (1980): the justice of the earnings is evaluated on the basis of a combination of actual expenses (equity principle), position in the status and/or prestige structure of a society (principle of entitlement), and individual need (needs principle), with the last-mentioned principle given the least weight of all. The relative importance of the principles varies among different societies and among different social groups. This is not necessarily true of the role of the proportionality principle in the allocation of earnings (Auspurg et al., 2013; Cohn et al., 2000; Hysom & Fişek, 2011; Jasso & Meyersson Milgrom, 2008). A comparative study of Eastern European countries (Bulgaria, Hungary, Poland, Russia) and Western countries (France, Spain, United States) conducted by Cohn and colleagues (2000) found a clear preference for the equity principle in all of the countries under study. This finding is consistent with the results of a study of American and Turkish students 9 conducted by Hysom and Fişek (2011) and with those of a comparative study conducted by Jasso and Meyersson Milgrom (2008) in the United States and Sweden. Both of these studies showed that the preference for the equity principle was more pronounced among American respondents, whereas the Swedish respondents gave more weight to operational context conditions (industry, capital, location) in the allocation of earnings. Auspurg et al.’s (2013) comparative study of perceptions of income equity in Western Germany, Eastern Germany, and Ukraine found that age had a significant effect on performance orientation. Older respondents in Germany gave more weight to status criteria (principle of entitlement), whereas in Ukraine, older respondents gave more weight to the needs principle and younger respondents gave more weight to the performance principle. This serves to illustrate the third problem of attitudinal justice research, namely that different attitudes toward justice may be the result of different conditions of socialization (e.g., East vs. West) and different experiences with the processing of distributional conflicts. This will be the focus of the following section. Experience-Based Attitudes: Attitudes toward Justice and the Problem of Selective Sampling Many studies in the area of empirical justice research are based on laboratory experiments that use small and very homogeneous samples. These experiments involve surveys among students of psychology, economics, or the social sciences (e.g., Greenberg, 1993; Markovsky, 1988), which means that the results of these experiments are not necessarily generalizable. The same criticism leveled against all experimental studies—namely the problem of the external validity of results (Henrich et al., 2010; Jones, 2010)—can also be leveled against these experiments. However, in the field of justice attitude research, such criticism is much more problematic. There are theoretical reasons to believe (Liebig & Sauer, 2013; Vanberg, 2007), and there is empirical evidence that indicates (Almås et al., 2010; Keller et al., 2013; Meulemann & Birkelbach, 2001), that attitudes toward justice are not personality traits that remain stable and persistent through an individual’s life course. Thus, attitudes toward justice, and judgments of what is just, are “position effects” (Boudon, 1990) in that they reflect not only the specific interests but also the experiences individuals “accumulate” in different occupational and social positions over the life course (Liebig & Sauer, 2013, 2015). The local justice approach developed by Jon Elster in the 1990s (Elster, 1991a, 1991b, 1992) is explicitly based on this assumption. Owing to their experience in solving distribution problems, certain population groups have attitudes toward justice that are different from those of individuals who cannot draw on such experiences (Keller et al., 2013). This is particularly true of students because they are at a specific stage of their life course, have very similar sociostructural characteristics and social backgrounds, and little experience with social distribution conflicts and possible ways to resolve such conflicts. Experimental studies involving surveys among students thus capture only a small range of the spectrum of possible attitudes toward justice, namely the range of attitudes that are not based on working life experience and experience with the resolution of distribution conflicts. Thus, more than many other areas of research, justice research is faced with the challenge of finding ways to benefit from the advantages of experimental methods outside the laboratory and to examine heterogeneous populations. This is another problem factorial surveys can help overcome. Since they can be used to combine experimental methods and standardized surveys, factorial surveys can be embedded in traditional survey methods such as interviewer-based, online, or mail-based surveys (Sauer et al., 2009, 2011, 2014). One possible application is the determination of the weight of individual dimensions by individual groups of respondents. Such “cross-level interactions” have been observed by Schrenker (2009), who found that respondents with a high income gave significantly more weight to the income that vignette individuals had before reaching pension entitlement age when deciding what constitutes a just pension than did respondents with a low income. Auspurg et al. (2013) found that 10 respondents with a higher level of education gave more weight to occupational prestige when allocating earnings than did respondents with a lower level of education. Both of these examples show that justice judgments also reflect respondents’ personal interests and that experience with the resolution of distributional conflicts (or lack of it) plays a crucial role. This is supported by Buzea et al. (2013) and Gatskova (2013). Buzea et al. (2013) found significant differences between students and the rest of the population, with the former leaning more toward the equal-distribution principle. On the whole, the results reported here show that when larger segments of a population are to be surveyed, factorial surveys can help to overcome the problems that result from selective sampling and small sample size. Social Desirability: Justice as a Normative Concept Justice as a normative concept is always a part of normative discourses and of social conflicts that are covered by the media, especially when it comes to social problems of distribution (Brettschneider, 2007; Leisering, 2004; Volkmann, 2004). Attitudes toward justice that are related to such discourses are faced with the problem of socially desirable response behavior (Paulhus, 1984), meaning that respondents do not express what they really think or believe but instead respond in accordance with what they anticipate as the majority opinion or existing norms. Researchers find that this problem is particularly pronounced when conducting item-based surveys (King & Bruner, 2000) or relying on self-reports by individuals (Fisher & Katz, 2000). It is also one of the main problems in justice research. One example is the question of the pay gap between men and women. The general observation is that in item-based surveys, an individual’s gender should not be of any importance. Thus the general consensus is that gender-based wage discrimination— the so-called gender wage gap—is to be regarded as unjust. However, studies that use factorial surveys indicate that respondents do allocate different earnings to male and female workers and that they believe that men should earn more than women with otherwise identical characteristics. This finding was reported in one of the first studies to have used a factorial survey (i.e., Jasso & Rossi, 1977) and has been confirmed several times since (Auspurg et al., 2013; Jann, 2008; Jasso, 1994; Jasso & Webster, 1997, 1999; Sauer, 2014). The conclusion that can be drawn is that if several judgment-relevant dimensions are presented simultaneously, the tendency to give socially desirable responses—in this case, gender should not matter—is suppressed in the vignettes (Alexander & Becker, 1978; Mutz, 2011). Another example of the suppression of social-desirability effects by using factorial surveys is provided by a study on just taxation conducted by Liebig and Mau (2005), who used a regional sample in Germany to examine attitudes toward criteria of what respondents believed constituted a just tax system. They concluded that “most of the applicable principles of the current tax system are regarded as legitimate” (Liebig & Mau, 2005, p. 468, transl. from the German), that the principle of progressive taxation is generally regarded as just, but that “flat-tax” models were not consistent with the German respondents’ attitudes toward justice at the time the study was conducted. However, in the context of our own study, the difference between item-based and vignette-based surveys is more relevant. Respondents in an item-based survey were asked which of the dimensions presented should be relevant for taxation. “Marital status: Married” was one of the dimensions. The majority of respondents did not think that marital status should be considered as a dimension of taxation. The respondents were then asked to evaluate the rates of taxation of the fictitious taxpayers presented. “Married” was a level of the dimension “Marital status”—besides “cohabiting.” The results showed that the respondents thought it would be just to allocate a lower tax burden to the married fictitious taxpayers. Unlike in the item-based survey, which disregarded traditional ideas of marriage and family, in the vignette-based survey, the respondents lowered the tax burden on married vignette individuals. As before, there is good reason to believe that item- 11 based surveys tend to reflect a more socially desirable opinion. This is more evidence that factorial surveys are likely to help to avoid socially desirable response behavior (Auspurg et al., 2015). Causality: Scientific Explanation and Empirical Testing Empirical justice research that intends to provide not only mere descriptions of collective opinions and attitudes but also explanations on the basis of theoretically derived statements on causal connections is confronted with the same problem that all empirical social research has, namely that of modeling causal relationships and of sufficiently testing these relationships using empirical methods (Gangl, 2010; Opp, 2010). Traditional survey-based research, which uses cross-sectional data, is practically incapable of reliably identifying possible causal relationships, since correlations between two variables might just as well be caused by other variables that have not been measured. Due to the simultaneous measurement of theoretically assumed causes and effects, and due to the problem of unobserved heterogeneity, complex methods are needed to identify causal relationships post hoc (Gangl, 2010). Although longitudinal studies can be used to measure causes and effects separately in time, and appropriate methods (fixed-effects models) can be used to exclude the time- constant unobserved heterogeneity (Allison, 2009; Brüderl, 2010),10 the best way to test causal relationships is to use experimental methods (Falk & Heckman, 2009). The first reason is that the researcher can control the central independent variables (with causal effect) and that the experimental manipulations are randomly distributed among the participants (“randomization”). The second reason is that the laboratory allows for most confounding factors to be ruled out and thus for the isolated measurement of causal effects (Webster & Sell, 2007). However, it should be noted that the problems described above occur when specific populations are surveyed. Once again, factorial surveys can provide a way out of this dilemma. Ceteris paribus modeling of hypotheses enables direct testing of theoretical relationships, and the randomized assignment of vignettes to respondents ensures independence of vignette and respondent characteristics. This rules out third-variable effects. In the specific case of justice research this means that the survey instrument takes the context dependence of attitudes toward justice into consideration, given that the respondents are provided with an appropriate description of the allocation and distribution situation. In addition, random assignment makes it possible to test models that explain causal relationships (Liebig & Sauer, 2013, 2015). As this article has shown, factorial surveys can be used, if not to overcome the five key conceptual and methodological problems of attitude-based empirical research on justice entirely, then at least to reduce these problems to a certain extent. Conclusion In this paper, we discussed the reasons why factorial surveys are used in justice research, the specific methodological features of studies that use these surveys, and the key results such studies have provided in the past. Our findings confirm that an individual’s decision whether goods and burdens are allocated justly does indeed depend on certain characteristics of the recipients of such goods and burdens, as well as on situational conditions. Factorial surveys can help to reveal how respondents differentiate when judging whether something is just or not. Factorial survey studies also reveal consensus structures that relate to the application of the norms and principles that 10 There are some longitudinal studies in the area of justice research which use fixed-effect models, among others (cf. Liebig et al., 2012; Sauer & Valet, 2013; Schunck et al., 2013). 12 underlie them and in which not only specific cultural features but also specific sociopositional features play a role. A particular advantage of using factorial surveys is that they enable the determination of the exact amounts of specific rewards and burdens recipients would allocate. The studies on just earnings or household income, socially just welfare benefits, or fair taxation allow researchers to derive conclusions as to what a given society believes are equitable rewards and burdens. Factorial surveys thus have benefits that far exceed those of item-based surveys. Recent years have seen an increasing use of factorial surveys in empirical social research, as well as a growing number of studies that focus on the methodological issues of and the questions that arise in connection with this method. To the extent that the experiences and insights derived in this way will inform the practice of conducting factorial surveys, the conceptual and methodological approaches can be expected to be optimized further in the future. As regards justice research, the use of factorial surveys in international comparative studies appears to be particularly promising (e.g., Auspurg et al., 2013; Hysom & Fişek, 2011; Jasso & Meyersson Milgrom, 2008) because most of the research in this area has been descriptive in nature (cf. Liebig & Sauer, 2013, 2015) and for precisely this reason is incapable of identifying the causal mechanisms that underlie judgments in different societies and thus cannot clearly differentiate between cultural and positional influences. We also think that it would be worthwhile to continue to explore the potential of interactive survey methods. One question in justice research that has yet to be answered is what influence the distribution of earnings in a given society has on respondents’ assessments of their own earnings. Does the actual degree of income inequality have any influence at all, or do individuals usually evaluate their earnings without regard to societal distribution parameters? Factorial surveys may help to answer these questions because they offer the opportunity to vary distribution contexts and to test the causal effects of “structural” parameters on individual justice judgments. However, a question that remains largely unresolved is whether factorial surveys enable more reliable behavior predictions in the context of justice research (cf. Eifler, 2010). This is where we see the greatest potential for development in this research field. References Adams, J. S. (1965). Inequity in Social Exchange. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 2, 267–299. Alexander, C. S., & Becker, H. J. (1978). The Use of Vignettes in Survey Research. Public Opinion Quarterly, 42(1), 93–104. Allison, P. D. (2009). Fixed Effects Regression Models. Thousand Oaks, CA; London; New Delhi; Singapore: SAGE. Almås, I., Cappelen, A. W., Sørensen, E. Ø., & Tungodden, B. (2010). Fairness and the Development of Inequality Acceptance. Science, 328(5982), 1176–1178. Alves, W. M., & Rossi, P. H. (1978). Who Should Get What? Fairness Judgments of the Distribution of Earnings. American Journal of Sociology, 84(3), 541–564. Auspurg, K., & Jäckle, A. (2012). First equals most important? Order effects in vignette-based measurement. ISER Working Paper Series, no. 2012-01. Colchester: Institute for Social and Economic Research. Auspurg, K., Gatskova, K., & Hinz, T. (2013). Vorstellungen von Lohngerechtigkeit in West- und Ostdeutschland und in der Ukraine. WSI-Mitteilungen, 66(2), 77–88. Auspurg, K., Hinz, T., & Sauer, C. (2013). Status Construction or Statistical Discrimination? New Insights on Fair Earnings from a Factorial Survey Study. Paper presented at the 108th Annual Meeting of the American Sociological Association, New York, NY. Auspurg, K., Hinz, T., Liebig, S., & Sauer, C. (2015). The Factorial Survey as a Method for Measuring Sensitive Issues. In U. Engel, B. Jann, P. Lynn, A. Scherpenzeel, & P. Sturgis 13 (Eds.), Improving Survey Methods: Lessons from Recent Research (pp. 137–150). New York, NY; Hove: Routledge. Beck, M., & Opp, K.-D. (2001). Der faktorielle Survey und die Messung von Normen. Kölner Zeitschrift für Soziologie und Sozialpsychologie, 53(2), 283–306. Boudon, R. (1990). Subjektive Rationalität und die Theorie der Ideologie. In H. Haferkamp (Ed.), Sozialstruktur und Kultur (pp. 384–414). Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. Brettschneider, A. (2007). Jenseits von Leistung und Bedarf: Zur Systematisierung sozialpolitischer Gerechtigkeitsdiskurse. Zeitschrift für Sozialreform, 53(4), 365–389. Brosnan, S. F. (2006). Nonhuman Species’ Reactions to Inequity and their Implications for Fairness. Social Justice Research, 19(2), 153–185. Brüderl, J. (2010). Kausalanalyse mit Paneldaten. In C. Wolf, & H. Best (Eds.), Handbuch der sozialwissenschaftlichen Datenanalyse (pp. 963–994). Wiesbaden: VS Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften/Springer Fachmedien. Buzea, C., Mesesan-Schmitz, L., & van de Vijver, F. J. R. (2013). Reward-Allocation Judgments in Romania: A Factorial Survey Approach. Revista de cercetare şi intervenţie socială, 40, 107–123. Cohn, E. S., White, S. O., & Sanders, J. (2000). Distributive and Procedural Justice in Seven Nations. Law and Human Behavior, 24(5), 553–579. Deutsch, M. (1985). Distributive Justice: A Social-Psychological Perspective. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Eifler, S. (2010). Validity of a Factorial Survey Approach to the Analysis of Criminal Behavior. Methodology: European Journal of Research Methods for the Behavioral and Social Sciences, 6(3), 139–146. Elster, J. (1991a). Local justice and interpersonal comparisons. In J. Elster, & J. E. Roemer (Eds.), Interpersonal Comparisons of Well-Being (pp. 98–126). Cambridge; New York, NY; Melbourne: Cambridge University Press. Elster, J. (1991b). Local justice: How institutions allocate scarce goods and necessary burdens. European Economic Review, 35(2–3), 273–291. Elster, J. (1992). Local justice: How Institutions Allocate Scarce Goods and Necessary Burdens. New York, NY: Russell Sage Foundation. Falk, A., & Heckman, J. J. (2009). Lab Experiments Are a Major Source of Knowledge in the Social Sciences. Science, 326(5952), 535–538. Fehr, E., & Schmidt, K. M. (2006). The Economics of Fairness, Reciprocity and Altruism – Experimental Evidence and New Theories. In S.-C. Kolm, & J. M. Ythier (Eds.), Handbook of the Economics of Giving, Altruism and Reciprocity: Volume 1: Foundations (pp. 615– 691). Amsterdam; Oxford: North-Holland. Fisher, R. J., & Katz, J. E. (2000). Social-desirability bias and the validity of self-reported values. Psychology and Marketing, 17(2), 105–120. Gangl, M. (2010). Causal Inference in Sociological Research. Annual Review of Sociology, 36(1), 21–47. Gatskova, K. (2013). Distributive justice attitudes in Ukraine: Need, desert or social minimum? Communist and Post-Communist Studies, 46(2), 227–241. Greenberg, J. (1993). Stealing in the Name of Justice: Informational and Interpersonal Moderators of Theft Reactions to Underpayment Inequity. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 54(1), 81–103. Hegtvedt, K. A. (2006). Justice Frameworks. In P. J. Burke (Ed.), Contemporary Social Psychological Theories (pp. 46–69). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Henrich, J., Heine, S. J., & Norenzayan, A. (2010). The weirdest people in the world? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 33(2–3), 61–83. Hermkens, P. J., & Boerman, F. (1989). Consensus With Respect to the Fairness of Incomes: Differences Between Social Groups. Social Justice Research, 3(3), 201–215. 14 Hysom, S. J., & Fişek, M. H. (2011). Situational determinants of reward allocation: The equity– equality equilibrium model. Social Science Research, 40(4), 1263–1285. Jann, B. (2008). Lohngerechtigkeit und Geschlechterdiskriminierung: Evidenz aus einem Vignetten-Experiment. In B. Jann (Ed.), Erwerbsarbeit, Einkommen und Geschlecht: Studien zum Schweizer Arbeitsmarkt (pp. 107–126). Wiesbaden: VS Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften. Jasso, G. (1978). On the Justice of Earnings: A New Specification of the Justice Evaluation Function. American Journal of Sociology, 83(6), 1398–1419. Jasso, G. (1980). A New Theory of Distributive Justice. American Sociological Review, 45(1), 3– 32. Jasso, G. (1994). Assessing Individual and Group Differences in the Sense of Justice: Framework and Application to Gender Differences in the Justice of Earnings. Social Science Research, 23(4), 368–406. Jasso, G. (2006). Factorial Survey Methods for Studying Beliefs and Judgments. Sociological Methods & Research, 34(3), 334–423. Jasso, G. (2007). Studying Justice: Measurement, Estimation, and Analysis of the Actual Reward and the Just Reward. In K. Törnblom, & R. Vermunt (Eds.), Distributive and Procedural Justice: Research and Social Applications (pp. 225–253). London; Burlington, VT: Ashgate. Jasso, G., & Meyersson Milgrom, E. M. (2008). Distributive Justice and CEO Compensation. Acta Sociologica, 51(2), 123–143. Jasso, G., & Rossi, P. H. (1977). Distributive Justice and Earned Income. American Sociological Review, 42(4), 639–651. Jasso, G., & Webster, M. J. (1997). Double Standards in Just Earnings for Male and Female Workers. Social Psychology Quarterly, 60(1), 66–78. Jasso, G., & Webster, M. J. (1999). Assessing the Gender Gap in Just Earnings and Its Underlying Mechanisms. Social Psychology Quarterly, 62(4), 367–380. Jasso, G., & Wegener, B. (1997). Methods for Empirical Justice Analysis: Part 1. Framework, Models, and Quantities. Social Justice Research, 10(4), 393–430. Jones, D. (2010). A WEIRD View of Human Nature Skews Psychologists’ Studies. Science, 328(5986), 1627. Keller, M., Gummerum, M., Canz, T., Gigerenzer, G., & Takezawa, M. (2013). The Is And Ought of Sharing: The Equality Heuristic Across The Lifespan. In R. Hertwig, U. Hoffrage, & ABC Research Group (Eds.), Simple Heuristics in a Social World (pp. 171–198). New York, NY: Oxford University Press. King, M. F., & Bruner, G. C. (2000). Social desirability bias: A neglected aspect of validity testing. Psychology and Marketing, 17(2), 79–103. Leisering, L. (2004). Paradigmen sozialer Gerechtigkeit: Normative Diskurse im Umbau des Sozialstaats. In S. Liebig, H. Lengfeld & S. Mau (Eds.), Verteilungsprobleme und Gerechtigkeit in modernen Gesellschaften (pp. 29–68). Frankfurt am Main: Campus. Leventhal, G. S. (1980). What Should Be Done With Equity Theory? New Approaches to the Study of Fairness in Social Relationships. In K. J. Gergen, M. S. Greenberg, & R. H. Willis (Eds.), Social Exchange: Advances in Theory and Research (pp. 27–55). New York, NY: Plenum Press. Liebig, S., & Mau, S. (2002). Einstellungen zur sozialen Mindestsicherung: Ein Vorschlag zur differenzierten Erfassung normativer Urteile. Kölner Zeitschrift für Soziologie und Sozialpsychologie, 54(1), 109–134. Liebig, S., & Mau, S. (2005). Wann ist ein Steuersystem gerecht? Einstellungen zu allgemeinen Prinzipien der Besteuerung und zur Gerechtigkeit der eigenen Steuerlast. Zeitschrift für Soziologie, 34(6), 468–491. Liebig, S., & Sauer, C. (2013). Soziologische Gerechtigkeitsanalyse: Überlegungen zur theoretischen Fundierung eines Forschungsfeldes. Analyse und Kritik, 35(2), 371–394. 15 Liebig, S., & Sauer, C. (2015). Sociology of Justice. In C. Sabbagh & M. Schmitt (Eds.), Handbook of Social Justice Theory and Research. New York: Springer. Liebig, S., Sauer, C., & Schupp, J. (2012). The justice of earnings in dual-earner households. Research in Social Stratification and Mobility, 30(2), 219–232. Liebig, S., Sauer, C., May, M., Hinz, T., Auspurg, K., Joos, A., & Schwarz, J. (2010). Bericht zur Studie Einkommensgerechtigkeit in Deutschland. Bielefeld: Bielefeld University/Konstanz: University of Konstanz. Markovsky, B. (1988). Injustice and Arousal. Social Justice Research, 2(3), 223–233. Markovsky, B., & Eriksson, K. (2012). Comparing Direct and Indirect Measures of Just Rewards. Sociological Methods & Research, 41(1), 199–216. Messick, D. M. (1993). Equality as a decision heuristic. In B. A. Mellers, & J. Baron (Eds.), Psychological Perspectives on Justice: Theory and Applications (pp. 11–31). Cambridge; New York, NY; Oakleigh, Vic.: Cambridge University Press. Meulemann, H., & Birkelbach, K. (2001). Biographische Erfahrungen und politische Einstellungen zwischen Jugend und Lebensmitte: Die Entwicklung von Wertansprüchen an die Politik bei ehemaligen Gymnasiasten im 16., 30. und 43. Lebensjahr zwischen 1969 – 1997. Politische Vierteljahresschrift, 42(1), 30–50. Mutz, D. C. (2011). Population-Based Survey Experiments. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Opp, K.-D. (2010). Kausalität als Gegenstand der Sozialwissenschaften und der multivariaten Statistik. In C. Wolf, & H. Best (Eds.), Handbuch der sozialwissenschaftlichen Datenanalyse (pp. 9–38). Wiesbaden: VS Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften/Springer Fachmedien. Paulhus, D. L. (1984). Two-component models of socially desirable responding. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 46(3), 598–609. Rawls, J. (1975). Eine Theorie der Gerechtigkeit. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. Roch, S. G., Lane, J. A. S., Samuelson, C. D., Allison, S. T., & Dent, J. L. (2000). Cognitive Load and the Equality Heuristic: A Two-Stage Model of Resource Overconsumption in Small Groups. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 83(2), 185–212. Rossi, P. H., & Anderson, B. (1982). The factorial survey approach: an introduction. In P. H. Rossi, & S. L. Nock (Eds.), Measuring Social Judgements: The Factorial Survey Approach (pp. 15–67). Beverly Hills, CA: Sage. Runciman, W. G. (1966). Relative Deprivation and Social Justice: A Study of Attitudes to Social Inequality in Twentieth-Century England. London: Routledge. Sauer, C. (2014). A Just Gender Pay Gap? Three Factorial Survey Studies On Justice Evaluations Of Earnings for Male and Female Employees. SFB 882 Working Paper Series, no. 29. Bielefeld: DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities. Sauer, C., Auspurg, K., Hinz, T., & Liebig, S. (2011). The Application of Factorial Surveys in General Population Samples: The Effects of Respondent Age and Education on Response Times and Response Consistency. Survey Research Methods, 5(3), 89–102. Sauer, C., Auspurg, K., Hinz, T., Liebig, S., & Schupp, J. (2009). Die Bewertung von Erwerbseinkommen – Methodische und inhaltliche Analysen zu einer Vignettenstudie im Rahmen des SOEP-Pretest 2008. SOEPpapers on Multidisciplinary Panel Data Research, no. 189. Berlin: DIW Berlin, The German Socio-Economic Panel (SOEP). Sauer, C., Auspurg, K., Hinz, T., Liebig, S., & Schupp, J. (2014). Method Effects in Factorial Surveys: An Analysis of Respondents’ Comments, Interviewers’ Assessments, and Response Behavior. SOEPpapers on Multidisciplinary Panel Data Research, no. 629 Berlin: DIW Berlin, The German Socio-Economic Panel (SOEP). Sauer, C., & Valet, P. (2013). Less is Sometimes More: Consequences of Overpayment on Job Satisfaction and Absenteeism. Social Justice Research, 26(2), 132–150. Schaeffer, N. C. (1990). Principles of Justice in Judgments About Child Support. Social Forces, 69(1), 157–179. 16 Schrenker, M. (2009). Warum fast alle das deutsche Rentensystem ungerecht finden, aber trotzdem nichts daran ändern möchten: Die Wahrnehmung gerechter Renten und die Akzeptanz von Rentenreformen. Kölner Zeitschrift für Soziologie und Sozialpsychologie, 61(2), 259–282. Schunck, R., Sauer, C., & Valet, P. (2013). Macht Ungerechtigkeit krank? Gesundheitliche Folgen von Einkommens(un)gerechtigkeit. WSI-Mitteilungen, 66(8), 553–561. Shepelak, N. J., & Alwin, D. F. (1986). Beliefs about Inequality and Perceptions of Distributive Justice. American Sociological Review, 51(1), 30–46. Törnblom, K. Y. (1992). The social psychology of distributive justice. In K. R. Scherer (Ed.), Justice: Interdisciplinary Perspectives (pp. 177–236). Cambridge; New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. Vanberg, V. J. (2007). Marktwirtschaft und Gerechtigkeit – Idee und Kritik der sozialen Gerechtigkeit im Konzept der Sozialen Marktwirtschaft. In S. Empter, & R. B. Vehrkamp (Eds.), Soziale Gerechtigkeit – eine Bestandsaufnahme (pp. 25–50). Gütersloh: Bertelsmann-Stiftung. Volkmann, U. (2004). Die journalistische Konstruktion gerechter Ungleichheiten. In S. Liebig, H. Lengfeld, & S. Mau (Eds.), Verteilungsprobleme und Gerechtigkeit in modernen Gesellschaften (pp. 297–328). Frankfurt am Main: Campus. Wallander, L. (2009). 25 years of factorial surveys in sociology: A review. Social Science Research, 38(3), 505–520. Webster, M., & Sell, J. (2007). Theory and Experimentation in the Social Sciences. In W. Outhwaite, & S. Turner (Eds.), The SAGE Handbook of Social Science Methodology (pp. 190–207). London; Thousand Oaks, CA; New Delhi; Singapore: SAGE. Wegener, B. (1987). The illusion of distributive justice. European Sociological Review, 3(1), 1–13. 17 1 Appendix Table 1. Distributive justice: An overview of factorial surveys Note: Publications have been selected on the basis of the procedure described in Footnote 3. Jasso and Rossi (1977), Jasso (1994), and Jasso & Webster (1997) are based on the same sample. NV = Number of vignettes used; NB = Number of respondents; NV/NB = Number of vignettes per respondent; ? = Exact number not reported. The column “Dimensions” is read as follows: e.g., 5 (2 × 34) means 5 dimensions with 1 × 2 levels and 4 × 3 levels. Sorted by topic and year. Characteristics that were used as dependent variables, had no influence, or were not examined in the article are given in brackets. Reference Object of investigation Relevant characteristics Dimensions (levels) NB NV NV/NB Answering scale Vignette sampling Respondent population Analysis Countries Alves & Rossi (1978) Earned income (individual) Earned Income, Occupational Status, Marital Status, Number of Children, Education, Taxation; [Gender], [Ethnicity] 8 (52 × 2 × 4 × 7 × ? × ? × ? × ?) 522 ? 50 9-point scale Random General population OLS regression USA Jasso (1994) Earned income (individual) Gender; [Relational Status], [Earned Income], [Education], [Number of Children], [Occupational Status] 6 (2² × 7 × 10 × 99 × 15) 200 600 60 9-point scale Random General population Two-stage estimation procedure USA Jasso &Webster (1997) Earned income (individual) Gender; [Relational Status], [Earned Income], [Education], [Number of Children], [Occupational Status] 6 (2² × 7 × 10 × 99 × 15) 200 100 60 9-point scale Random General population OLS regression USA Jasso & Webster (1999) Earned income (individual) Age, Education, Gender, Earned Income; [Occupational Status] 5 (2 × 10² × 4 × 15) 377 30 10 Magnitude scale Random Students Robust regression, respondent- specific regression, and vignette-specific regression USA Cohn et al. (2000) Earned income (individual) Effort (Certificate of Employment, Willingness to Accept Occupational Changes/Salary Cuts), Need (Labor Market Situation, Marital Status); [Voice], [Impartiality of the Company] 4 (42); 5 (5²) 831; 786; 824; 765; 762; 775; 810 32; 1000 2 10-point scale Complete design; random General population OLS regression Bulgaria, Hungary, Poland, Russia, France, Spain, USA 18 Jann (2008) Earned income (individual) Gender, Need (Single Parent, Narrow Finances), Effort (Engagement, Complies with Performance Requirements) 3 (3³) 531 8 1 11-point scale Complete design General population OLS regression Switzerland Jasso & Meyersson Milgrom (2008) Earned income (individual) Age, Gender, Job Experience, Company Site, Industrial Sector, Education, Financial Assets of the Company; [Earned Income] 8 (11 × 2 × 15 × 16× 3 × 4 × 272) 47; 36 80 40 Magnitude scale Random Students Multilevel models and respondent- specific regression USA, Sweden Sauer et al. (2009) Earned income (individual) Earned Income, Occupational Status, Education, Effort, Marital Status, Number of Children, Gender, Situation of the Company, Company Size; [Age] 10 (2 × 35 × 4 × 5 × 10²) 1066 240 24 Magnitude scale Fractionalized design General population Robust regression Germany Hysom & Fişek (2011) Earned income (individual) Kind of Task, Co-Worker Relations, Kind of Occupation; [Gender], [Occupational Status], [Age], [Education], [Occupational Experience], [Group Size] 9 (24 × 35) 295; 314 8 8 Allocation of relative proportion of the reward Selective choice of vignette dimensions on the basis of pretests Students OLS regression USA, Turkey Auspurg et al. (2013) Earned income (individual) Germany (West): Occupational Status, Effort, Education, Marital Status, Gender, Age, Number of Children; [Situation of the Company], [Form of Company], [Earned Income] Germany (East): Occupational Status, Effort, Education, Marital Status, Number of Children, Age, Gender; [Situation of the Company], [Form of Company], [Earned Income] Ukraine: Number of Children, Effort, Occupational Status, Marital Status, Gender, Education, Age; [Situation of the Company], [Form of the Company], [Earned Income] 10 (Germany: 4 × 2 × 35 × 10² × 5; Ukraine: 4 × 2² × 34 × 10² × 5) 944; 1797 240 24 100-point scale Fractionalized design General population Robust regression Germany, Ukraine Buzea et al. (2013) Earned income (individual) Contribution, Occupational Experience, Familiarity with the task, Need (Number of Children), Future Interactions, Age; [Gender] 7 (2 × 8 × 35) 200 8000 40 Percentage pay increase Random Students Multilevel models Romania 19 Gatskova (2013) Earned income (individual) Older Generation: Number of Children, Effort, Occupational Status, Relational Status, Gender, Form of the Company, Age; [Education], [Earned Income], [Financial Situation of the Company] Younger Generation: Number of Children, Effort, Occupational Status, Gender, Relational Status, Form of the Company, Age; [Education], [Earned Income], [Financial Situation of the Company] 10 (2 × 36 × 6 × 10²) 12 11-point scale Fractionalized design General population Robust regression Ukraine Jasso & Rossi (1977) Earned income (household) Multiple Person Households: Education (Husband), Occupational Status (Husband & Wife), Marital Status, Family Income; [Education (Wife)], [Number of Children] Multiple Person Households: Gender, Relational Status, Earned Income, Education, Number of Children, Occupational Status 6 (2² × 7 × 10 × 99 × 15) 200 600 60 9-point scale Random General population OLS regression USA Shepelak & Alwin (1986) Earned income (household) Single Households: Ethnicity, Education, Size of Family, Vocational Training, Gender, Occupational Prestige Family Household: Education (Husband & Wife), Vocational Training, Gender, Occupational Status of Husband & Wife; [Family Size] 6 328 135 15 Monetary units Selective choice General population OLS regression USA Hermkens & Boerman (1989) Earned income (household) Occupational Status, Number of Employed Persons in Household, Number of Children, Occupational Effort; [Gender], [Age] 6 (2² × 27 × 50 × ? × ?) 795 4200; 8400 5; 10 Monetary units Random General population OLS regression Netherlands Schaeffer (1990) Child support Earned Income Father, Earned Income Mother, Marital Status Father, Marital Status Mother, 6 (23 × 32 × 5) 1003 3 Monetary units Random General population Tobit regression USA 20 Number of Children [Occupational Status Father] Liebig & Mau (2002) Minimum collateral Number of Children, Occupational Status, Age, Occupational Position, Amount of State Transfers; [Reason for Lay-Off], [Amount of Income Supplement], [Gender] 8 (22 × 32 × 1 × 4 × 6 × 5) 121 48 24 Magnitude scale Random General population Robust regression Germany Liebig & Mau (2005) Taxes Earned Income, Number of Children, Amount of Inheritance, Marital Status; [Social Engagement], [Age], [Gender], [Occupational Status] 8 (2² × 3 × 4² × 5 × 19 × 33 ) 586 20 20 Magnitude scale Random General population Robust regression Germany Schrenker (2009) Pensions Amount of last Income, Years of Professional Experience, Number of Children, Combined Supply of Partner, Gender; [Amount of Monthly Pension] 6 (22 × 11 × 5 × 6 × 10) 2690 250 25 Monetary units and 11- point scale Random General population Random coefficient models and OLS models (including beta- values and t- values) Germany 21 Previously published SFB 882 Working Papers: Diewald, Martin / Faist, Thomas (2011): From Heterogeneities to Inequalities: Looking at Social Mechanisms as an Explanatory Approach to the Generation of Social Inequalities, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 1, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Bielefeld. Busch, Anne (2011): Determinants of Occupational Gender Segregation: Work Values and Gender (A)Typical Occupational Preferences of Adolescents, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 2, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A3, Bielefeld. Faist, Thomas (2011): Multiculturalism: From Heterogeneities to Social (In)Equalities, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 3, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project C3, Bielefeld. Amelina, Anna (2012): Jenseits des Homogenitätsmodells der Kultur: Zur Analyse von Transnationalität und kulturellen Interferenzen auf der Grundlage der hermeneutischen Wissenssoziologie, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 4, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project C3, Bielefeld. Osmanowski, Magdalena / Cardona, Andrés (2012): Resource Dilution or Resource Augmentation? Number of Siblings, Birth Order, Sex of the Child and Frequency of Mother’s Activities with Preschool Children, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 5, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A1, Bielefeld. Amelina, Anna / Bilecen, Başak / Barglowski, Karolina / Faist, Thomas (2012): Ties That Protect? The Significance of Transnationality for the Distribution of Informal Social Protection in Migrant Networks, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 6, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project C3, Bielefeld. Alemann, Annette von / Beaufaÿs, Sandra / Reimer, Thordis (2012): Gaining Access to the Field of Work Organizations with the Issue of “Work-Family-Life Balance” for Fathers, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 7, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project B5, Bielefeld. Kaiser, Till (2012): Haben gebildetere Mütter gewissenhaftere Kinder? Soziale Herkunft und Persönlichkeitsentwicklung im frühkindlichen Alter, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 8, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A1, Bielefeld. Gusy, Christoph / Müller, Sebastian (2012): Social Construction of Heterogeneity Indicators and their Relationship to Law. The Example of Guiding Principles in Immigration Law, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 9, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project C4, Bielefeld. Liebig, Stefan / May, Meike / Sauer, Carsten / Schneider, Simone / Valet, Peter (2012): Inequality Preferences in Interviewer- and Self-Administered Interviews, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 10, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A6, Bielefeld. Fauser, Margit / Voigtländer, Sven / Tuncer, Hidayet / Liebau, Elisabeth / Faist, Thomas / Razum, Oliver (2012): Transnationality and Social Inequalities of Migrants in Germany, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 11, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project C1, Bielefeld. Freistein, Katja / Koch, Martin (2012): Global Inequality and Development. Textual Representations of the World Bank and UNDP, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 12, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project C5, Bielefeld. Golsch, Katrin (2013): Shall I Help You My Dear? Examining Variations in Social Support for Career Advancement within Partnerships, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 13, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A3, Bielefeld. Bröckel, Miriam / Busch, Anne / Golsch, Katrin (2013): Headwind or Tailwind – Do Partner’s Resources Support or Restrict a Promotion to a Leadership Position in Germany?, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 14, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A3, Bielefeld. Cardona, Andrés (2013): Closing the Group or the Market? The Two Sides of Weber’s Concept of Closure and Their Relevance for the Study of Intergroup Inequality, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 15, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A1, Bielefeld. Friedhoff, Stefan / Meier zu Verl, Christian / Pietsch, Christian / Meyer, Christian / Vompras, Johanna / Liebig, Stefan (2013): Social Research Data. Documentation, Management, and Technical Implementation at SFB 882, SFB 882 Working Paper Series, No. 16, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Project “Information and Data Infrastructure” (INF), Bielefeld. Reinecke, Jost / Stemmler, Mark / Sünkel, Zara / Schepers, Deborah / Weiss, Maren / Arnis, Maria / Meinert, Julia / Kucur-Uysal, Burcu / Pöge, Andreas / Wallner, Susanne / Wittenberg, Jochen (2013): The Development of Deviant and Delinquent Behavior over the Life Course in the Context of Processes of Social Inequalities, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 17, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A2, Bielefeld. Hense, Andrea / Edler, Susanne / Liebig, Stefan (2013): Individual Determinants of Recalls, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 18, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project B4, Bielefeld. Bilecen, Başak (2013): Analyzing Informal Social Protection Across Borders: Synthesizing Social Network Analysis with Qualitative Interviews, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 19, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project C3, Bielefeld. Schunck, Reinhard / Abendroth, Anja-Kristin / Diewald, Martin / Melzer, Silvia Maja / Pausch, Stephanie (2013): What do Women and Men Want? Investigating and Measuring Preference Heterogeneity for Life Outcomes using a Factorial Survey, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 20, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project B3, Bielefeld. Sauer, Carsten / Valet, Peter / Liebig, Stefan (2013): The Impact of Within and Between Occupational Inequalities on People’s Justice Perceptions Towards their Own Earnings, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 21, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A6, Bielefeld. Schneider, Simone / Valet, Peter (2013): Social Comparison Orientations and their Consequences for Justice Perceptions of Earnings, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 22, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A6, Bielefeld. Cardona, Andrés (2013): The Programmatic Bias in the Discussion on Social Mechanisms in Sociology, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 23, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A1, Bielefeld. Hille, Adrian / Schupp, Jürgen (2013): How Learning a Musical Instrument Affects the Development of Skills, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 24, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A1, Bielefeld. Faist, Thomas (2014): "We are all Transnationals now": The Relevance of Transnationality for Understanding Social Inequalities, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 25, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project C1, Bielefeld. Lohmann, Henning / Ferger, Florian (2014): Educational Poverty in a Comparative Perspective: Theoretical and Empirical Implications, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 26, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A5, Bielefeld. Freistein, Katja / Koch, Martin (2014): The Effects of Measuring Poverty – Indicators of the World Bank, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 27, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project C5, Bielefeld. Andernach, Björn / Schunck, Reinhard (2014): Investigating the Feasibility of a Factorial Survey in a CATI, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 28, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project B3, Bielefeld. Sauer, Carsten (2014): A Just Gender Pay Gap? Three Factorial Survey Studies on Justice Evaluations of Earnings for Male and Female Employees, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 29, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A6, Bielefeld. Berger, Johannes (2014): Dringend erforderlich: eine stärker vereinheitlichte soziologische Ungleichheitsforschung, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 30, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project Z, Bielefeld. Karsch, Anna (2014): Geschlechtstypische Unterschiede in den Berufspräferenzen deutscher Jugendlicher, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 31, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A3, Bielefeld. Barglowski, Karolina (2014): Social Classifications and Inequalities: Ideologies of Mobility, Care and Work in Transnational Families, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 32, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project C3, Bielefeld. Sauer, Carsten / Valet, Peter / Liebig, Stefan (2014): Ungleichheiten am Arbeitsmarkt und die Gerechtigkeitswahrnehmung von Erwerbseinkommen, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 33, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A6, Bielefeld. Dawid, Herbert / Harting, Philipp / Neugart, Michael (2014): Cohesion Policy and Inequality Dynamics: Insights from a Heterogeneous Agents Macroeconomic Model, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 34, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A4, Bielefeld. Liebig, Stefan / May, Meike / Sauer, Carsten / Schneider, Simone / Peter Valet (2014): The Effect of Interviewer Presence on Inequality Preferences, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 35, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A6, Bielefeld. Cardona, Andrés / Diewald, Martin (2014): Opening the Black Box of Primary Effects: Relative Risk Aversion and Maternal Time Investments in Preschool Children, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 36, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A1, Bielefeld. Fehl, Caroline / Freistein, Katja (2014): Institutional Mechanisms of Global Inequality Reproduction, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 37, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project C5, Bielefeld. Freistein, Katja (2014): Are there any Global Imaginaries of Equality and Democracy in Discussions about Inequality? SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 38, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project C5, Bielefeld. Meinert, Julia (2014): Selection into criminogenic contexts by personal heterogeneity and its effects on delinquency, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 39, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A2, Bielefeld. Schepers, Debbie (2014): Social Inequalities as Causes of the Causes of Juvenile Delinquency. Heterogeneities in the Context of Situational Action Theory, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 40, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A2, Bielefeld. Abendroth, Anja-Kristin / Pausch, Stephanie / Böhm, Sebastian (2014): German Fathers and Their Preference to Reduce Working Hours to Care for Their Children, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 41, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A3, Bielefeld. Bürmann, Marvin: Determinanten beruflichen Aufstiegs (2014): Der Einfluss von Unterstützung durch Kollegen und Vorgesetzte. Eine Sekundäranalyse anhand der Daten des Sozio-oekonomischen Panels. SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 42, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A3, Bielefeld. Rosenbohm, Sophie / Gebel, Tobias / Hense, Andrea (2015): Potenziale und Voraussetzungen für die Sekundäranalyse qualitativer Interviewdaten in der Organisationsforschung. SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 43, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project B4/INF, Bielefeld. Schneider, Simone / Shamon, Hawal (2015): How Others' Earnings influence our Justice Perceptions. Studying the Effects of Income Distribution and Social Position on Reflexive Justice Evaluations among German Employees. SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 44, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A6, Bielefeld. Kruphölter, Sonja / Sauer, Carsten / Valet, Peter (2015): Occupational gender segregation and gender differences in justice evaluations. SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 45, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A6, Bielefeld. Liebig, Stefan / Sauer, Carsten / Hülle, Sebastian (2015): Why is justice regarded as so important? Theoretical considerations and an empirical test of a fundamental question. SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 46, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A6, Bielefeld. Foliennummer 1 Liebig-Sauer-Friedhoff-2015.pdf Introduction Contextual Information: Complexity of Distribution Processes Conclusion References 1 Appendix 10-point scale work_64ob2n7ganbynbfnopigln27a4 ---- 2004 VOL. 28 NO . 6 AUSTRALIAN AND NEW ZEALAND JOURNAL OF PUBLIC HEALTH 507 Editorials Individual rights and social justice Jeanne Daly and Judith Lumley Co-editors, Australian and New Zealand Jour nal of Public Health Running through the election speeches of various political leaders leading up to the Australian Federal election in October 2004 were two competing discourses. The f irst, and the dominant one, emphasised the individual. The second emphasised the provision of public services. These views were not always confined to a single political party. Individuals, so it was argued, have the right to choose to send their children to a private school that reflects their personal values – and should be helped to do so by gover nment f inancial support to these schools. Individuals have the right to hold private health insurance, with greater freedom in the choice of health care provider. There was the right of the individual to climb the ‘ladder of opportunity’. There was the assumption that the tax burden on individuals should be reduced. Direct f inancial support was needed for families with young children; if individuals are the product of stable families they would hold the values that were seen to underpin a productive society. The other discourse emphasised large social and systemic issues, especially gover nment funding for health and social services. There was support for equal access to a sound educational system and, in health, support for a robust public hospital system, universal health insurance and bulk billing by general practitioners. Overall, economic issues were seen to be of paramount importance, especially the interest rates that would be levied against families holding high mor tgages. The question lurking behind the provision of better public services was who was going to pay for these services? Would tax rates be raised? Raising tax es was seen as the result of bad economic management. Good f iscal management was emphasised to the exclusion of responsibility for good moral conduct in government. It is worth noting that, while individual choice was favoured, this did not include women’s right to choose an abortion or the right to gay marriage. Public health by its very nature is aligned with those who f avour collective responsibility for the provision of good public ser vices. We have argued in this Journal that a robust public system for dealing with infectious disease is essential and collective action to sustain the environment has direct health consequences. But, we have also argued for health promotion programs that deal with individual behaviour, such as smoking tobacco or unsafe driving. Often the individual and the systemic are combined, for example, when a tax on tobacco products is used as part of a program of smoking cessation. Between these two extremes, we have focused on the health needs of communities and geographic regions. Any discipline or practice that covers anything from the individual to the systemic r uns the risk of delivering a thin coverage of any one issue. In this Journal, we have argued that the diversity of public health is its strength, especially as we have developed a corresponding diversity in our research methods so that the evidence on which we base our practice has a sound basis. In this issue, we argue that public health activities at these various levels are inte grated and given coherence by a set of shared values. The most important of these values is a concern for social justice. Social justice is one of those ideas that is often invoked and seldom analysed, although it is something we all treasure. While advocacy is an important par t of public health practice, we see the role of the Jour nal as analysing the evidence for our strong beliefs, submitting them to peer review, and opening up a debate about these sometimes diff icult issues. So it is in this issue of the Jour nal, which opens with Julian Disney’s editorial on pover ty public health and social justice in the light of the Federal election. Sarah Mares and Jon Jureidini report the psychiatric assessment of children and families in immigration detention who were referred for assessment to a child and adolescent health service as showing very high levels of psychopathology, much of it attributable to traumatic experiences in detention. Zachar y Steel and colleagues document the poor mental health status of a near complete sample of children and their f amilies from one ethnic group held for an extended period of time in a remote detention centre, describing detention-related traumatic symptoms and the effect of detention on parenting. These two papers are complemented by Linda Shields’ comparison of Australia’s solution with the very different approaches of two Nordic countries and Deborah Zion’s reflection on the dilemmas of care within unjust frameworks. The impact of health policy and funding on inequalities is highlighted by David Brennan and John Spencer in their account of the deterioration in dental health among older people associated with the loss of public dental programs in the late ’90s. There is some good dental news from Anne Sanders: most of us – unlike our parents – are ver y unlikely to lose all our teeth. Lawrence Lam’s Brief Report proposes a new approach to measuring the impact of premature death based on loss of productive years of life. In a Point of View, Gavin Mooney’s reflects on possible public health lessons for Australia from the history of South Africa. Phyll Dance and colleagues describe a successful process to analyse the needs for aged care ser vices for Indigenous people in the ACT, including the implementation of change. Public health action is the core of public health, demonstrated in this issue by the description by Trang Vu and colleagues of the costs and benefits of improved infection control in the prevention of variant Creutzfeldt-Jakob disease in Australia, Paul Dietze and colleagues’ description of characteristics of non-f atal opioid overdoses attended by ambulance services in Australia and a report of the incidence of hepatitis C among injecting drug users on opioid replacement therapy, by Richard Hallinan and colleagues. John Toumbourou calls for ethical guidelines on the vexed question of compensation for research par ticipants. Finally, the friends and colleagues of the late Jill Cockbur n remind us of her great contributions to public health research and practice. This issue, as the last for 2004, contains a full author and subject index, as well as a list of our reviewers for the year. 508 AUSTRALIAN AND NEW ZEALAND JOURNAL OF PUBLIC HEALTH 2004 VOL. 28 NO. 6 More challenges for public health in fight against poverty Julian Disney National Chair, Anti-Poverty Week, and Director, Social Justice Project, University of New South Wales Public health initiatives have historically played major roles in preventing or reducing poverty and social injustice, both in Australia and overseas. This applies especially to meeting basic needs such as safe water, sanitation, nutrition and primar y health care. But major challenges remain and new ones are emerging. Within Australia, there can be little doubt that the highest priority is to improve the health of Indigenous people. For example, despite living in a relatively wealthy country their life expectancy is about the same level as applies in Bangladesh. Better opportunities to study, work and enjoy good housing could substantially improve their overall health outcomes. But their ability to take advantage of any such opportunities can be drastically affected by ill-health arising from earlier lack of health care or by the prevalence of illness and early death among relatives. Despite our allegedly successful economy, homelessness and unemployment remain major causes and consequences of pover ty, hardship and injustice in Australia. On any given night about 100,000 people are homeless and 100 families with children are turned away from refuges. There are more than half a million jobless families and more than 100,000 people who have been unemployed for more than 12 months. The real level of unemployment is about double the off icial rate when account is taken of the exceptionally high proportion of par t-time employees who want more work and the number of people who have gone on a disability or sole-parent pension because they cannot f ind work. The linkages between unemployment, homelessness and ill- health are widely acknowledged. There is less recognition, however, of the health problems arising for workers and their families from big increases in job insecurity and overwork during the past 20 years or so. Australia ranks very poorly in these respects by comparison with almost all other developed countries. The resulting incidence of severe stress and relationship breakdowns is being aggravated by inadequate public investment in transpor t, child care and other measures to help combine work with family responsibilities. Other special concerns arise from large increases over recent years in the number of one-adult households as a consequence of changing attitudes towards mar riage, less secure employment, higher house prices and greater life expectancy. Sole-parent families tend to have especially high levels of f inancial hardship and stress, and to be more economically vulnerable in the event of ill-health. Older people who are living alone are also especially at risk. The apparently inexorable g rowth in the number of one- adult households has substantial implications for health services and outcomes in coming decades The levels of pover ty and hardship will almost certainly worsen within the next few years as the realities of Australia’s economic circumstances begin to be felt. While our governments have about the lowest levels of debt among developed countries, our levels of corporate and household debt are higher than almost all of them. We have been living far beyond our means and, among other things, competitively bidding up house prices to levels that are depriving an increasing proportion of the population from the security of home ownership in times of f inancial adversity, ill- health or frailty. These problems have been exacerbated by poor economic policies, including taxation reform, on the par t of both Commonwealth and State Gover nments. Many people who are concerned about pover ty and hardship regard close consideration of these issues as being beyond or beneath them. Yet some of the current policies have fundamentally adverse effects on both the incidence of hardship, including ill-health, and the availability of public and private resources to ameliorate it. This applies, for example, to the suppl y of secure and adequately remunerated work, access to affordable housing and health care, and the availability of informal family support. Poverty and severe hardship is, of course, a more severe and widespread problem in many other countries. Substantial improvements have been achieved in countries such as China and India during the past decade or two but many African countries, in particular, have experienced either deterioration or no significant improvement Within our own neighbourhood, Indonesia and Papua New Guinea have especially severe levels of poverty and several other countries are experiencing rapid increases in AIDS- related problems. Many of the improvements in developing countries during the past 50 years or so have stemmed largely from public health initiatives. They include greater proportions of people having access to safe water, sanitation, basic nutrition and essential vaccination. As a result, considerable progress has been made in relation to maternal and child mortality, life e xpectancy, restriction of infectious diseases and other key concerns. They have been accompanied, and often assisted, by notable improvements in the availability of basic education, including a reduction in discrimination against education of girls. Never theless, more than two billion people still lack adequate sanitation. At least one billion people have incomes below $US1 a day. More than 800 million people are under-nourished and more than 100 million young children are not receiving primar y education. Life expectancy is falling substantially in several Editorials Journal contact details Mail: Australian and New Zealand Journal of Public Health, PO Box 351, North Melbourne , Victoria 3051. Street deliveries: c/- SUBStitution Pty Ltd, 1st Floor, 484 William Street, Melbourne, Victoria 3003. Phone: (03) 9329 3535 Fax: (03) 9329 3550 E-mail: anzjph@substitution.com.au 2004 VOL. 28 NO . 6 AUSTRALIAN AND NEW ZEALAND JOURNAL OF PUBLIC HEALTH 509 Editorials African countries principally as a result of AIDS, for which fatality rates around the world are often closely linked with pover ty. In 2000, a unique UN summit of heads of gover nment led to the adoption of eight Millennium Development Goals (MDGs), most of which involve specific numerical targets to be achieved by 2015. They include, for e xample, reductions of at least two- thirds in child mortality, three-quarters in maternal mortality, and one-half in the proportions of people who lack access to safe water or suffer hunger. They also include halving the proportion of people with incomes below $US1 a day, achieving universal access to primary education, and reversing the spread of HIV/AIDS and malaria. The Australian Council of Social Service and Australian Council for Overseas Aid played signif icant roles in lobbying at the UN over many years for adoption of the MDGs. They did so in the belief that among the vast ar ray of internationally agreed targets, a small number of specific and measurable tar gets that are ambitious but not wildly unrealistic should be agreed upon as top priorities for action. It was recognised that most developed countries would already have achieved the goals, although not perhaps within some groups (re grettably including Indigenous Australians). But it was hoped that those countries, and international organisations such as the World Bank and IMF, would make specific commitments to help other countries achieve them. Within the Asia-Pacif ic region, the UN estimates that at present only two of the targets are likely to be achieved by 2015. They relate to improvements in income and in girls’ access to education. The targets that are regarded as unlikely to be achieved include those relating to child and maternal mor tality rates and access to water. In Africa, it is unlikely that any of the targets will be achieved on time. Yet most rich countries of the world continue to f all far short of the agreed target for provision of overseas aid and continue to impose economic policies in areas such as trade and taxation that actively discriminate against poorer countries. Many Australians in the pub lic health field have made and continue to make outstanding contributions to the fight against poverty and hardship at home or abroad. Never theless, much remains to be done and during the next decade the international economic environment may become less conducive to progress (except for major emerging powers such as China, India, and perhaps Brazil). The f ight to achieve greater emphasis on reducing poverty and social injustice will not be easy. The voices and actions of many concerned Australians will need to spread beyond their established fields of expertise to include key underlying causes of hardship, especially in economic policy. They will need to go beyond their accustomed circles in order to join people with whom they may have little in common e xcept an active or awakeable sense of fair ness and compassion. This need motivated the recent establishment of an annual Anti- Pover ty Week in Australia to highlight problems of poverty and severe hardship and to strengthen efforts to address them. It is concer ned with poverty both at home and abroad and is held in mid-October each year to coincide with the UN’s International Anti-Pover ty Day (17 October). The special week was established in the belief that most Australians are more concer ned about poverty and hardship than is commonly recognised by political and economic pundits. It aims to encourage people to demonstrate this concern, and the breadth of the general constituency for action, by organising their own local or regional activities on whatever par ticular issues they wish. Anti-Pover ty Week deliberately does not adopt any of ficial policies of its own or require proposed activities to be submitted for approval. Its organising principle is “let a thousand flowers bloom”. In its first two years, the week has g rown to involve more than 80 different events around Australia, many of which are in outer suburbs, regional cities and country towns. Special efforts are being made to encourage par ticipation by people whose main interests are in health and education. The consequences of pover ty are often especially damaging in these areas and preventive or remedial action can be particularly effective. They also involve many articulate and resourceful people whose voices could augment substantially the small number of social workers, church leaders and academics who tend to be seen as the core of anti-poverty advocacy. When carefully and dispassionately analysed, the recent federal election results are not inconsistent with the view that most Australians care about pover ty and social injustice. But they do emphasise the need for the type of broad and inclusive outreach beyond traditional enclaves and constituencies that the week seeks to develop. Sources For further information about Anti-Poverty Week, see www.antipoverty week.org.au In relation to poverty and related hardship in Australia, see Senate Community Affairs Reference Committee, A Hand Up not a Hand Out (Senate, Canberra, 2004); Australian Institute of Health and Welfare, Australia’s Welfare 2003 (AIHW, Canberra, 2003); Australian Bureau of Statistics, Measures of Australia’s Progress 2004 (ABS, Canber ra, 2004) ; R. Tiffen and R. Gittins, How Australia Compares (Cambridge University Press, Sydney, 2004). In relation to international poverty and related hardship, see the United Nations Development Program, Human Development Report (UNDP, New York, 2004); United Nations Economic and Social Commission for Asia and the Pacif ic, Promoting the Millennium Development Goals in Asia and the Pacific (UN, New York, 2003). 510 AUSTRALIAN AND NEW ZEALAND JOURNAL OF PUBLIC HEALTH 2004 VOL. 28 NO. 6 Editorials Caring for detained asylum seekers, human rights and bioethics Deborah Zion Faculty of Medicine, Monash University, Victoria, and Co-editor of Monash Bioethics Review What is our innocence? / What is our guilt? All are naked / None is safe (Marianne Moore) Michael Hall, a nurse working first at Curtin detention centre and then on Christmas Island, was ask ed to escort two pregnant women to the mainland. They were being forcibly separated from their families, including their other children, to be taken to the mainland to have their babies. Their families were not allowed to accompany them because once on the mainland they could apply for refugee status. The women would not do so alone because they wished to maintain the family unit. They were also not infor med of their legal rights. Hall refused to escort the women on the grounds that he found the practice ethically unacceptable. 1 His stance raises many issues concer ning the relationship between medical ethics and human rights, and tests the limits of professional obligation when just systems are not in place.2 The psychiatrist Louise Newman has characterised the dilemma as “an intrinsic conflict between the desire to provide appropriate care, and the compromising of this by supporting a pathological system”.3 It is one example of the problem of ‘dual loyalties’, where healthcare professionals experience a “clinical role conflict between professional duties to a patient and obligations, express or implied, real or perceived, to the interests of a third party such as an employer, insurer or the state”.4 Issues related to dual loyalty conflicts vary considerably. The most serious and obvious example relates to healthcare providers’ direct involvement in torture, 5 a practice that directly opposes medicine’s primary aim to “protect and promote health”.6 However, in situations where doctors and nurses are also disempowered, some argue that there may be an obligation to minimise harm. A doctor may believe that his presence may actually lessen the level of harm inflicted on the victim during violent interrogation and so may feel an obligation to be present. The problem of professional ethical practice in cor rupt political environments is also por trayed by Jane Steere and Terence Dowdall in their description of working as psychologists in South Africa during apartheid. The ethical complexities inherent in trying to treat mental illness under such a regime were exacerbated by the fact that the broader social system in which they had to work violated their profession’s ethical principles, leaving them with the dilemma of providing either no treatment or treatment that they considered to be unethical.7 The issue of wrongdoing by involvement with an unjust institution is fundamental to an analysis of Hall’s dilemma and many other cases where doctors, psychologists and nurses have tried to treat asylum seekers held in detention centres. These include the forced treatment of hunger strikers and returning children suffering from mental illness to detention or keeping them separated from their families. For those committed to healing, any course of clinical action in these circumstances does not ser ve the best interests of the patients in question, who remain imprisoned for long periods, often separated from family members. Their distress, anxiety and depression can be seen as normal reactions to the terrible circumstances in w hich they f ind themselves, for w hich the most effecti ve treatment is the re- establishment of liberty and other basic rights.8 The Dutch psychiatrist Annemiek Richters elucidates the problem when she states that: ... for asylum seekers and refugees, mental disorders characterised by standardised psychiatric diagnosis may often be better described as normal reactions to abnormal political, social and cultural situations. As physical integrity cannot withstand the dissolution of the social personality, it is at the le vel of the political, social, and cultural that healing should occur. 9 The problem of ‘dirty hands’ The dilemma f aced by Michael Hall is an example of what Stephen de Wijze refers to as the problem of ‘dirty hands’. De Wijze suggests that when a person with the intention of acting morally has to choose between the lesser of two evils because of the immoral acts or projects of others, he suffers as both a perpetrator and a victim.10 He states: ... by being forced to engag e in the evil projects of others, an agent suffers the violation of her moral autonom y and selfhood. By participating in ‘dirty acts’, the agent is changed, morally speaking, by doing evil (having intentionally caused the evil circumstances to persist) and her victims are changed by suffering evil. (p 217) How can we think about Hall’s refusal to continue to provide care to the women in detention? Does participation in an obviously unjust and harmful system validate his refusal? Is this the central ethical question that we need to consider and, if not, what other ethical course of action is open to Hall and those who f ind themselves in similar situations? Medical ethics and refusing to treat Recent accounts of healthcare workers’ obligations and refusal to treat in the bioethics literature focus on the safety of the healthcare work er on the one hand, and upon conflicts of conscience on the other.11 When personal safety is an issue, there is some consensus that it is reasonable to expect doctors and other healthcare professionals to take on some personal risk, although there is also recognition that healthcare institutions must provide means to ensure the physical safety of such workers. Professional issues involving conflict of conscience are more problematic and take several forms. For example, a professional may be bound to perform tasks that she finds personally morally offensi ve, while recognising their importance if a just society is to continue. A doctor might be obliged to keep a patient on life support that he knows will be of 2004 VOL. 28 NO . 6 AUSTRALIAN AND NEW ZEALAND JOURNAL OF PUBLIC HEALTH 511 little use and is taking up valuable resources because he has inherited a duty to prolong life under most circumstances and believes that such a duty is just. Hall’s dilemma is dif ferent again, as he is being required to support, through his actions, a separation that he believes to be both unjust and harmful. To ask how patient autonomy can be respected in such a situation draws us away from bioethical discussions that focus on decontextualised encounters between doctors and patients, and forces us to consider the important connection between autonomy and freedom. Protecting autonomy: two bioethical accounts Respect for the decisions made b y rational patients is a fundamental component of respect for autonomy, and is the cornerstone of Western bioethics. The view of autonomy most commonly in use by healthcare practitioners relies on principalism, as set out in Tom Beauchamp and James Childress’ work, Principles of Biomedical Ethics.12 According to this model, respect for patient decision-making is achieved and facilitated through maintaining conf identiality, providing information and maintaining a high standard of truthfulness about treatments and their outcome. Howe ver, Tom Faunce has suggested that the principalist approach is essentially isolationist. By this he means that the “... approach presents these principles as arriving like some deux ex machina rather than evolving ... from foundational social and professional virtues”.13 There have been many critiques of the principalist view of autonomy, and its lack of analysis in which choices are made. In response to such criticisms, Susan Sherwin, Anne Donchin and Chris MacDonald have developed a different way of thinking about autonomy, sometimes referred to as ‘relational autonomy’. This view relies upon an idea of autonomy as socially dependent.14 Rather than imagining an autonomous person as free from constraints, they suggest that an autonomous person is deeply involved in relationships with others, whose acts f acilitate her forming and fulf illing her own goals.14-16 Susan Sherwin suggests that for autonomy to have value, certain social conditions must be in place that provide meaningful options. These conditions should be embedded in both personal and political supportive structures.15 Autonomy, therefore, is not a simply a matter of preserving negative rights to non-interference.14 The principalist vie w of autonomy seems to have little application in Hall’s case. Even if Hall observed all the rules that facilitate autonomy, the women concerned were so constrained that the term itself seems meaningless. The second, or ‘relational’ view of autonomy, is slightly more illuminating. On this view, the ethical standing of Hall’s actions in protecting the already limited autonomy of the women rests on a powerful but simple question: what do the women and their families themselves want? If they found Hall’s presence to be of value, especially in the light of the rest of their treatment, and they wished for his assistance, there may be a case to be made that he should indeed have accompanied the women. If, on the other hand, the families ask ed him to take a stand, his refusal can be seen as an act of advocac y. However, it is clear that the women in question did not have suff icient options to determine a meaningful life course. Thus discussions of autonomy – even relational autonomy – in reference to asylum seekers in detention has a somewhat hollow ring, and illuminates the inadequacies of bioethics when divorced from a discussion of human rights and political freedoms.15,16 The importance of social justice in discussions of bioethics has a relatively shor t but important histor y, and developed rapidly in relation to clinical research and HIV/AIDS in de veloping countries, and focused on the issue of autonomy and infor med consent in this setting. Many commentators suggested that relying on a view of autonomy based only upon the subjects’ ability to make rational decisions with little or no anal ysis of the kinds of choices, freedoms and rights available to those involved, rendered the concept of autonomy meaningless. The political philosopher Joseph Raz suggests that autonomous action must be based upon “an adequate range of options to choose from” (p 373).17 Raz is not refer ring to the numbers of options, but what these options actually consist of. He gives two examples that demonstrate just how numbers of options alone are meaningless in securing or promoting autonomy. The first story concer ns a ‘Man in a Pit’, whose choices are limited to “whether to eat now or a little later, whether to sleep now, or a little later, whether to scratch his left ear or not” (p 374).17 His second example concer ns a ‘Hounded Woman’ who spends her whole life on a desert island, trying to escape a carnivorous creature which is trying to devour her. Raz suggests that while both these subjects have choices, they cannot be called autonomous, for “... one has only tri vial options to choose from ... The other person’s predicament is the opposite one. All her choices are potentially horrendous in their consequences” (p 374).17 Refocusing bioethics In their recent analysis of human rights, social justice and bioethics, Paul Farmer and Nicole Gastineau Campos ask: “If access to health care is considered a human right, who is considered ‘human enough’ to have that right?” (p 249)18 They call upon those involved in healthcare practice and in bioethics to refocus discussion on the relationship between freedom, social justice and health.19 How might an analysis that begins with these ideas elucidate the dilemmas faced by healthcare professionals acting within an unjust framework? Of primary importance is the idea that public health and healthcare systems are unquestionably political.20 As Paul McNeill states: [Public health] is political in the broad sense by being concerned with a group of interests within a community that may be competing with other interests. It is also political in the particular sense of being involved in po wer and authority, either in the exercise of authority or in reaction to those who exercise it, and thus engaged actively in issues of politics and government. (page 495)20 Editorials 512 AUSTRALIAN AND NEW ZEALAND JOURNAL OF PUBLIC HEALTH 2004 VOL. 28 NO. 6 McNeill suggests that the correct ethical response for dilemmas like Michael Hall’s is advocacy and political action.21 If we consider Hall’s decision in the context of his witnessing and publishing accounts of inhumane treatment, we also see him involved in an act of advocacy that goes be yond the ethical predicament of whether or not to accompany the women in his care. The importance of collective action There is, in the recent history of public health, a model for the way in which collective political action can strengthen freedom and expand the numbers of choices that are made availab le. The advent of HIV/AIDS in Australia, for example, led to gay community-based action that changed the way in which HIV prevention and research was carried out, and the means through which drugs were made available to desperately ill patients. Early in the epidemic, many HIV-positive, gay community- attached men, particularly in Melbourne and Sydney, organised infor mal means through which early HIV/AIDS therapeutic trials were subver ted and challenged. The gay press, particularly the Sydney Star Observer, also provided challenging commentary concer ning HIV/AIDS treatments.22 Gay community-attached, HIV-positive men also started to circulate newsletters specif ically dedicated to empowering other people living with HIV and AIDS, in which they advocated a philosophy of empowerment and active partnership with the medical profession.23 AIDS councils were established in all Australian states initially run by volunteers, with strong connection to gay activist politics. 24 These councils went on to form an important part of the public health bureaucracy and mobilised other community groups. This, in turn, profoundly influenced both research and treatment, especially the insistence that promising dr ugs would be made available to those who needed them through compassionate access schemes, that the development of treatments w as consistent with the needs of affected communities, and that those most affected by the disease would enter into research partnerships with clinicians. Conclusion It is undeniable that collective action by medical colleges and associations enhances eff icacy and lessens the burdens on individuals, thus increasing the possibility for effective and ethical healthcare for asylum seekers. Another important issue relates to the problem of working in unethical and unjust conditions, and the effect this has upon the inte grity of the healthcare provider’s “moral autonomy and selfhood”.10 In his recent commentary on the issue of torture in Abu Ghraib prison, Rober t Jay Lifton describes the acculturation process that creates “atrocity-producing situations”,25 in which ordinary people begin to engage in acts that they would, in other circumstances f ind morally repugnant. In the case of providing healthcare in a detention centre, engaging with other healthcare professionals could facilitate the development of collecti ve ethical approaches, provide emotional support, and make possible strategies through which professional guidelines were backed up with a blueprint for action.26 Finally, collective engagement might provide a just environment with which nurses and doctors would have frequent contact, in order to keep at bay the normalisation of a world in which human rights violations are commonplace. Acknowledgements The author wishes to acknowledge ongoing discussions with Professor Sandy Gifford, Centre for Refugee Health, Latrobe University, and Jo Szwarc from the Victorian Foundation for Survivors of Torture, which have contributed to this article. References 1. Hall M. Frontline nursing in detention, Aust Nursing J 2004;11(7):32-3. 2. Mooney G. Pub lic health, political morality and compassion. Aust N Z J Public Health 2002;26:201-02. 3. Loff B. Detention of asylum seekers in Australia. Lancet 2002;359:792-3,793. 4. Physicians for Human Rights, Dual Loyalty & Human Rights In Health Professional Practice; Proposed Guidelines & Institutional Mechanisms, http:/ /www.phrusa.or g/healthrights/dual_loyalty.html 5. Miles S. Abu Ghraib: its legacy for military medicine. Lancet 2004;364:725-9. 6. Zwi A. The political abuse of medicine and the challenge of opposing it. Soc Sci Med 1987;25(6): 649-57. 7. Steere J and Dowdall T. On being ethical in unethical places: Dilemmas of South African clinical psychologists. Hastings Cent Rep 1990;20(2):11-15,13. 8. K outroulis G. Detained asylum seekers, health care and questions of human(e)ness. Aust N Z J Public Health 2003; 27:381-4. 9. Richters A. When ethics, healthcare, and human rights conflict: Mental healthcare for asylum seekers. Camb Q Healthc Ethics 2002;11(3):304-18, 312-3. 10. De Wijze S. Defining evil: Insights from the problem of ‘dirty hands’. Monist 2002;85(2):210-38, 216. 11. Arras R. The fragile web of responsibility: AIDS and the duty to treat. Hastings Cent Rep 1988;18(2):10-20. 12. Beauchamp T and Childress J. Principles of Biomedical Ethics, 3r d edition. New York: Oxford University Press, 1989. 13. Faunce T. Developing and teaching the virtue-ethics. Foundations of healthcare w histle-blowing. Monash Bioeth Review 2004;23(4): in press. 14. MacDonald C. Relational professional autonomy. Camb Q Healthc Ethics 2002;11(3),282-9, 282-3 15. Sherwin S, A relational approach to autonomy in health care in Sherwin S (ed.) The Politics of Women’s Health: Exploring A gency and Autonomy. Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1998. 16. Donchin A, Reworking autonomy: Tow ards a feminist perspective, Camb Q Healthc Ethics 1995;4(1):44-55. 17. Raz J. The Morality of Freedom. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986. 18. Farmer P, Gasineau Campos N. New Malaise: Bioethics and human rights in the global era. J Law Med Ethics 2003;32(2):243-51. 19. See also Benatar S, Daar A and Singer PA. Global Health ethics: the rationale for mutual caring. International Affairs 2003;79(1):107-38, p.108. 20. McNeill P. Pub lic health ethics: Asylum seekers and the case for political action. Bioethics 2003; 17(5-6): 487-502. 21. This suggestion is based upon the work of Callahan C and Jennings B. Ethics and public health: forging a strong relationship. Amer J Public Health 2002;92:169-76. 22. Ariss R. Against Death. The Practice of Living With AIDS, Amsterdam: Gordon and Breach Publishers, 1997, p 78. 23. See for e xample, Willett G. Living Out Loud. A History of Gay and Lesbian Activism in Australia, St Leonards, NSW: Allen and Unwin, 2000. Kippax, S, Crawford J, Connell R, Dowsett G, Watson L, Rodden P, Baxter D and Berg R, The importance of gay community in the prevention of HIV transmission: A study of Australian men who have sex with men in Aggleton P, Davies P and Hart G (eds.) AIDS. Rights, Risk and Reason, London: The Falmer Press, 1992. Kippax S, Connell R, Dowsett G and Crawford J, Sustaining Safe Sex; Gay Communities Respond to AIDS, London: The Falmer Press, 1993. 24. Woolcock G and Altman D. The largest street party in the world in Adam B, Duyvendak J and Krouwel A (eds) The Global Emer gence of Gay and Lesbian Politics, Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1999, 326-44, 336. 25. Lifton RJ. Doctors and tor ture. N Engl J Med 2004;351(1):415-6, and Conditions of atrocity. The Nation, 31/5/2005. 26. Rogalla B. Nursing behind razor wire: A question of ethics, Aust Nurs J 2001;8(9):21. Editorials work_633kyswbwrfnxptgqmgi26vamy ---- Tilburg University Growing justice Barendrecht, J.M. Publication date: 2009 Document Version Early version, also known as pre-print Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): Barendrecht, J. M. (2009). Growing justice: Justice policies and transaction costs. (TISCO Working Paper Series; Vol. 009/2009). Tilburg Institute for Interdisciplinary Studies of Civil Law and Conflict Resolution Systems (TISCO). http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1475201 General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal ? Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 06. apr. 2021 https://research.tilburguniversity.edu/en/publications/14f47850-af59-4af7-8faa-8eb70ee6793a http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1475201 ��� � TISCO WORKING PAPER SERIES ON CIVIL LAW AND CONFLICT RESOLUTION SYSTEMS Growing Justice: Justice policies and Transaction Costs Maurits Barendrecht Tilburg University, Tilburg Institute for Interdisciplinary Studies of Civil Law and Conflict Resolution Systems (TISCO), International Victimology Institute Tilburg (Intervict), Tilburg Law and Economics Centre (Tilec); Hague Institute for the Internationalisation of Law (HiiL) j.m.barendrecht@uvt.nl TISCO Working Paper Series on Civil Law and Conflict Resolution Systems No. 009/2009 September 18, 2009, Version: 1.0 & Tilburg University Legal Studies Working Paper No. 013/2009 This paper can be downloaded without charge from the Social Science Research Network Electronic Paper Collection http://ssrn.com/abstract=1475201 ��� � Maurits Barendrecht1 Growing Justice: Justice Policies and Transaction Costs Abstract This paper reviews the literature on policies aiming to improve the rule of law and the operation of a legal system. It takes a bottom up perspective of clients seeking access to justice and uses transaction costs on the market for justice as a criterion to evaluate justice policies. Most justice is created through ‘justice transactions,’ including informal help from friends, legal advice, information about law, ADR services, other forms of informal justice, and adjudication. Such transactions are seriously hampered by three major transaction cost problems, however. Justice policies include codification, setting up courts and reforming them, financing of courts, legal aid, ADR, developing rules of procedure, and regulation of the legal profession. The transaction cost perspective explains why many traditional justice policies do a poor job to increase access to justice or to diminish the costs of civil justice. More promising justice policies enable justice to emerge bottom up, in the interactions between clients and providers of justice services (microjustice, legal empowerment). These policies focus on the information needs of disputants, low cost default procedures, choice for plaintiffs, accountability towards clients, gradual, needs-based formalization of legal relationships, and strengthening informal compliance mechanisms. 1 Helpful comments on an earlier version were provided by Martin Gramatikov, Machteld de Hoon, Jan Smits, Jin Ho Verdonschot, Ben Vollaard, and workshop participants at the Hague Institute for Internationalization of the Law (17 april 2008) and Amsterdam Centre for Law and Economics (18 april 2008). ��� � Table of Contents I. INTRODUCTION........................................................................................................................... 4 II. APPROACH ................................................................................................................................ 5 A. JUSTICE POLICIES ...................................................................................................................... 5 B. JUSTICE NEEDS .......................................................................................................................... 6 C. JUSTICE TRANSACTIONS ............................................................................................................ 7 D. TRANSACTION COSTS OF JUSTICE SERVICES ............................................................................. 8 III. LETTING DISPUTANTS ENTER A COOPERATIVE PROCEDURE ............................ 11 A. MARKET ANALYSIS ................................................................................................................. 11 B. CURRENT INTERVENTIONS BY STATES .................................................................................... 13 1. Reducing the Rewards of Continued Conflict......................................................................... 13 2. Judgments by Default ............................................................................................................. 13 3. Stimulating Mediation and Conciliation ................................................................................ 14 C. PROMISING POLICIES ............................................................................................................... 15 1. Social Norms and Unilateral Pledges to Deal with Conflict Cooperatively.......................... 15 2. Opening the Market for Neutral Dispute Resolution Services ............................................... 15 3. Regulating Ex Ante Dispute Resolution Agreements.............................................................. 16 4. Requiring Repeat-Players to Offer an Accessible Dispute System ........................................ 17 5. Co-opting Powerful Defendants ............................................................................................. 17 IV. THE MARKET FOR NEGOTIATION ASSISTANCE ....................................................... 18 A. MARKET ANALYSIS ................................................................................................................. 18 B. CURRENT INTERVENTIONS BY STATES .................................................................................... 19 1. Framing Disputes in Terms of Rights and Obligations.......................................................... 19 2. Legal Aid................................................................................................................................. 20 3. Mediation Aid ......................................................................................................................... 21 C. PROMISING POLICIES ............................................................................................................... 21 1. Education in Integrative Negotiations and Conflict Management......................................... 22 2. Economies of Scale in Communication and Negotiation Advice ........................................... 22 3. Structuring Settlement Negotiations ....................................................................................... 23 V. SUPPLYING INFORMATION ABOUT FAIR SOLUTIONS ............................................ 24 A. MARKET ANALYSIS ................................................................................................................. 24 B. CURRENT INTERVENTIONS BY STATES .................................................................................... 25 1. Codification ............................................................................................................................ 25 2. Precedents............................................................................................................................... 27 3. Supporting Law Faculties at Universities .............................................................................. 27 C. PROMISING POLICIES ............................................................................................................... 28 1. Improving Incentives to Generate Guidelines ........................................................................ 28 2. Rulemaking through Intermediate Private Institutions .......................................................... 28 3. Removing Restraints on Rulemaking for Distributive Issues ................................................. 29 4. New Models for Sharing Rules ............................................................................................... 29 VI. DELIVERING THE OPTION OF A NEUTRAL DECISION ............................................ 30 A. MARKET ANALYSIS ................................................................................................................. 30 B. CURRENT INTERVENTIONS BY STATES .................................................................................... 31 1. Courts...................................................................................................................................... 31 2. Extensive Rules of Procedure ................................................................................................. 32 3. Protecting Clients and Monitoring Neutrals through Appeals .............................................. 33 4. Independence of Courts .......................................................................................................... 33 C. PROMISING POLICIES ............................................................................................................... 34 1. Simple, Low-Cost Default Procedures ................................................................................... 35 2. Accountability towards Clients............................................................................................... 36 3. Giving Plaintiffs Choice ......................................................................................................... 37 4. Terminating Unhelpful Approaches ....................................................................................... 38 VII. MAKING ARRANGEMENTS EXPLICIT AND ENFORCEMENT ................................. 39 ��� � A. MARKET ANALYSIS ................................................................................................................. 39 B. CURRENT INTERVENTIONS BY STATES .................................................................................... 41 1. Registrations of Identity.......................................................................................................... 41 2. Registrations of Property Rights ............................................................................................ 41 3. Default Rules for Contractual Relationships.......................................................................... 42 4. Enforcement by State .............................................................................................................. 42 C. PROMISING POLICIES ............................................................................................................... 43 1. Formalization As Is and Step by Step ..................................................................................... 43 2. Menus for Making Relationships Explicit .............................................................................. 44 3. Facilitating Compliance Mechanisms .................................................................................... 45 4. What Works............................................................................................................................. 45 VIII. COMPLEMENTARITIES .................................................................................................. 46 A. MARKET ANALYSIS ................................................................................................................. 46 B. CURRENT INTERVENTIONS BY STATES .................................................................................... 47 1. Legal System Reform: Law and Development ........................................................................ 47 2. Reforms in Developed Economies .......................................................................................... 47 C. PROMISING POLICIES ............................................................................................................... 47 1. Supply Chain Approach to Access .......................................................................................... 47 2. Monitoring, Accountability and System Ownership ............................................................... 48 3. Focus on Problem Categories ................................................................................................ 48 IX. CONCLUSIONS ....................................................................................................................... 49 I. Introduction One of the classical responsibilities of states towards their citizens is to establish the rule of law and to ensure access to justice. Governments do this by designing and enacting ‘justice policies’. Courts are created and maintained, public prosecution is set up, and the legal profession is regulated. Procedures are defined in codes of civil procedure, criminal codes are enacted that make clear which conduct is a crime, and contract law facilitates private transactions between citizens. Governments also subsidize courts and legal aid. If their legal system is criticized, they may introduce alternative dispute resolution, or reform legal aid, courts, civil procedure, and the tort system. This paper suggests a new way to evaluate such justice policies: by looking at their potential to reduce the transaction costs on what can be called the market for justice. Over the centuries, the actions taken by individuals to protect their rights have led to what we now identify as a legal system. Precedents, laws, contracts, property rights, and procedures were developed. It has become commonplace to expect the rule of law as something created and upheld by the state. If the justice is not accessible, or the rule of law is not established, it is the state that failed. But historically, it is not unrealistic to look at law as a by-product of people bringing their claims to advisers, lawyers, courts, kings, and politicians. The way people take action to protect their rights is therefore a good starting point for analyzing whether people get the legal protection they need. Let us thus look at the position of the client (plaintiff) who experiences a need for justice in a relationship to another person (defendant). Urgent justice needs may arise when crimes have been committed, or when problems arise in contractual relationships. Clients will then turn to friends, lawyers, or others for information and advice, and probably also to persons who can exert influence over their opponent. These people deliver a service to the client, which can be studied as a market transaction. Obviously, buying justice is not a straightforward transaction such as purchasing a car or obtaining a loan from a bank. Behind the need for justice, usually a conflict of interest with the defendant is looming. The defendant may not cooperate to delivery of a just outcome. What a just outcome is, may also be unknown. A lawyer, or even a judge, has interests that are not perfectly aligned with those of her clients. So clients have to monitor the performance of the lawyer and the judge, and should probably invest in means to ensure that they do ��� � their job. These extra costs that a client faces on his way to justice can be studied as transaction costs. In this paper, I use this transaction cost analysis to evaluate justice policies. Section II explains the approach in more detail. In Section III to VII, we follow the plaintiff who tries to obtain a just outcome. We distinguish five main types of justice services that help him on the way. These services enable the plaintiff to (1) meet the defendant in order to seek a cooperative solution, (2) communicate and negotiate (talk), (3) distribute gains and losses fairly (share), (4) decide on outcomes, and (5) stabilize the relationship with the defendant. For each type of justice services, we identify the sources of transaction costs that make them difficult to deliver to clients in a sustainable and affordable way (Subsection A). After this ‘market analysis’, we identify the most common interventions of governments on this justice market and investigate whether these are likely to lower the transaction costs (B). Thereafter, we discuss some possible alternative justice policies that have more potential to lower transaction costs and thus to improve the rule of law and access to justice (Subsection C). Section VIII discusses the transaction costs that arise because a legal system has to be more than its five constituent parts. In economic terms, there are complementarities between the five types of justice services. Thus, we obtain a broad picture of the market for justice and the way governments intervene. This leads to an overview of helpful and less helpful policies (Section IX). II. Approach A. Justice Policies Governments all over the world struggle with their justice policies. Legal services tend to be expensive; courts slow and, occasionally, unpredictable, or downright corrupt. In developed economies, budgets for legal aid and courts are limited. Lawyers have obtained extensive powers to self-regulate their profession, but governments are increasingly asked to review this regulation, because it may have a negative impact on competition, harm the interests of clients, and slow down innovation of legal services (Hadfield 2008). Justice policies are also high on the international agenda. The international community faces the problem of failing states, unable to deliver the basic stability that is implied in the rule of law. Human rights are another item: they may be recognized by states in treaties, but should also be guaranteed in the practice of ordinary lives. There is also a growing understanding that effective justice policies are key to economic development. Although the precise links are disputed, both policy makers and researchers agree that enforceable property rights, labor rights, and business rights help economies to grow and to distribute the benefits of economic growth more evenly (Kaufmann 2003; Buscaglia and Stephan 2005; Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor 2008; Haggard, MacIntyre et al. 2008; Kaufmann, Kraay et al. 2008). Access to justice is a precondition for this (Jensen 2002; Kaufmann 2003; Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor 2008). Most justice policies have a top down orientation. Rules are written down in constitutions, codes, and legislation. Then courts are set up, public prosecutors are appointed, and the legal profession is stimulated to organize itself. Once this is done, governments should maintain the resulting ‘legal system’. The rule of law literature agrees that this top-down implementation has not been very successful (López de Silanes 2002; Botero, La Porta et al. 2003; Golub 2003; Carothers 2006; Dam 2006; Hammergren 2007; Davis and Trebilcock 2008; Haggard, MacIntyre et al. 2008). Investments in formal legislation and institutions like courts do hardly result in actual protection of the rights of ordinary citizens or small to medium sized companies. There is abundant evidence that access to justice, either through the norms, lawyers and court of a formal legal system, or through informal ��� � arrangements, is insufficient in many places and in many situations (Rhode 2004; Yuille 2004; Fitzpatrick 2005; Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor 2008). Although some institutional economists argue that, historically, the rule of law has been first implemented for elites (North, Wallis et al. 2009), most scholars and politicians now place their bets on bottom up approaches. Civil society can create informal ways of protection that are more effective than the formal legal system, so they argue (Davis and Trebilcock 2008; Tamanaha 2009). Citizens should become legally empowered, or facilitated through microjustice when they face justiciable legal problems (Golub 2003; Van Rooij 2007; Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor 2008). What lacks, however, is a theory that can explain why these bottom up approaches might work, and which policies are more likely to succeed than others. The rule of law literature has not yet delivered a consistent theory behind interventions. It shows much conceptual debate about what the rule of law is (Ringer 2007; Tamanaha 2008), but much less discussion about the ways to make it happen. The assumption seems to be that systematic institution building is possible, if governments only would be able to decide which institutions they want. A part of the literature mentions sequencing as a problem, but this suggests again that these writers know what should be done, the issue merely being where to start (Carothers 2007). Once the top down perspective is changed for bottom up approaches, the lack of theory behind justice policies becomes even more problematic. The focus of attention now shifts to creating access to justice. But what type of justice do people need, and how can access to it be created? The literature on access to justice tends to distinguish five waves of access to justice reforms, oriented at supplying legal aid, public interest litigation, alternative dispute resolution, opening up the market for legal services, and better regulation of the legal profession (Cappeletti and Garth 1978; Parker 1999). This gives some indication of the shifting beliefs in what works to create access to justice, but does not explain why such approaches might work, or why some of them have failed. There are two common threads, however, and these I will pick up in this paper. First, the basic idea of access to justice expressed here is one of services provided to clients. As Landes and Posner have showed, lawyers, mediators, and even adjudicators like courts can be considered to be providers on the market for justice (Landes and Posner 1979). They are the ones who try to deliver fair outcomes to clients. Second, the reforms all seem to be oriented towards making this market work in a better way: by subsidies, by stimulating certain types of justice services, or by (de)regulating the market. Combining these threads, and adding a theoretical perscpective, I propose to evaluate justice policies acccording to their potential to lower transaction costs on the market for justice services. B. Justice Needs Justice needs can be defined as a need for protection by outside norms or interventions that structure the conduct of other persons (Barendrecht, Kamminga et al. 2008). When does such a need arise? Legal needs studies, in which a sample of the population is interviewed by researchers about their legal problems and ways to cope with them, have been conducted throughout the world (Curran 1977; American Bar Association 1994; Genn and Beinart 1999; Genn and Paterson 2001; Dignan 2004; Van Velthoven and Ter Voert 2004; Currie 2005; Coumarelos, Wei et al. 2006; Michelson 2007; Gramatikov 2008; Michelson 2008). These studies show consistent patterns of justice needs (Barendrecht 2008; Barendrecht, Kamminga et al. 2008). Demand for justice services is most urgent in three types of conflict, where the stakes are high and where people depend on others for their well-being. Personal security presents the most salient category of problems. People seek basic protection of their human rights, and try to protect themselves against violence, unlawful ��� � taking of property, and unlawful detention. Secondly, they enter long term relationships with substantial specific investments, such as family, work, land use, neighbor, and business relationships. These relationships have to cope with change. Because changes in circumstances, preferences, and abilities are difficult to predict, rights and obligations cannot be determined at the moment the relationship starts (known as the issue of incomplete contracts). Adaptation to change through negotiation is a necessity, but the parties are dependent on each other, because they invested in the relationship, and cannot walk away from it without leaving these investments behind. So some sort of neutral dispute system is necessary (Williamson 1987; Nooteboom 1992; Barendrecht 2008; Robson and Skaperdas 2008). Examples of conflicts in these long term relationships are inheritance issues, divorce, termination of employment, and problems regarding compensation for the use of land to be paid to owners. A third category of conflicts emerges from contracts between buyers and sellers, or from obligations of the bureaucracy to its citizens. Here, the issues are mostly what the plaintiff could expect (interpretation of contracts and of applicable regulation), how the defendant contributed to these expectations by giving or withholding information (duties to inform), and whether the defendant delivered goods or behavior that live up to the legitimate expectations of the plaintiff (Barendrecht 2009). The empirical studies cited above show that most conflicts are solved through negotiation. Conflict resolution can aptly be described as a negotiation process in which the parties try to achieve Pareto efficient outcomes (create value), and bargain about distributive issues (share value), but this process is complicated by the parties being dependent on each other. They cannot solve the conflict with somebody else if their negotiations fail, like they can go to another seller of a car if they fail to reach agreement on the price. Because of this bilateral monopoly, they need mechanisms to decide on the outcome if they cannot reach an agreement. This creates the need for justice services. C. Justice Transactions A first, intuitive understanding of justice services would probably distinguish two basic types: legal advice and neutral, third party interventions. But from the interdisciplinary literature on conflicts, dispute system design (Ury, Brett et al. 1988; Costantino and Sickles Merchant 1996; Menkel-Meadow 1996; Bendersky 2003; Barendrecht 2008; Bingham 2008; Bordone 2008; Barendrecht 2009), institutional design (Hadfield 2008) and legal procedure, five necessary and sufficient dispute resolution tasks can be derived. In essence, justice services help clients to perform these five tasks. For each of these five basic types of dispute services, basic technologies have become available. Task Description Basic technology 1. Meet Centralized forum for information processing in which both parties participate Make costs and benefits of participation for defendant higher than costs and benefits of fighting, appropriation, or avoiding 2. Talk Communication and negotiation Support integrative negotiation (interest based) 3. Share Distributing value fairly Supply information about fair shares (sharing rules, objective criteria) 4. Decide Decision making procedure Make option of a neutral decision available (at low cost) 5. Stabilize Transparency and compliance Supply tools to make arrangements explicit; Make costs and benefits of compliance higher than those of non-compliance Table 1 Necessary and Sufficient Elements of a Dispute System with Basic Technologies for Delivery (Barendrecht 2008). The plaintiff and the defendant have to meet somehow. Friends or lawyers may help a plaintiff to make meeting more attractive for the defendant. Mediators and lawyers can then help the parties to communicate and negotiate in a structured way. If they provide information about ways other people have settled similar disputes (norms, objective criteria), the plaintiff and the defendant can solve the distributive issues more easily. � � � Decision-making in the bilateral monopoly is facilitated by the availability of a low cost neutral decision, that provides an exit option for both parties. Stabilizing relationships is a matter of making expectations explicit and creating motivation to live up to the outcome. Formats for contracts and registrations, as well as strategies to induce compliance, can be supplied to serve these interests of clients. Dispute system design is still a young discipline, but there is a beginning of a common understanding of “what works” in order to perform these five basic types of services (Ury, Brett et al. 1988; Wall Jr and Callister 1995; Tyler 1997; Wall, Stark et al. 2001; Bendersky 2003; Bingham 2008; Bordone 2008; Barendrecht 2009; Wall Jr and Chan- Serafin 2009). These best practices can build on years of conflict research by social psychologists, economists, and socio-legal researchers (Barendrecht 2009). Negotiation and conflict resolution technology can deal with emotions and psychological barriers. Procedural justice satisfies the procedural needs of the parties. If norms for distributing value are unclear, suitable objective criteria can be developed. If justice is not achieved through negotiations and bargaining, a neutral third party can break the impasse, if necessary by giving a binding decision. If a powerful defendant does not cooperate, he can be forced to do so by increasing sanctions, rewards, and other incentives. We may probably assume that the basic justice technologies are now sufficiently developed. If justice is out of reach for many people, the cause is unlikely to be that justice providers do not know what to do for their clients, or face high costs of interventions. Although there are some exceptions, where interventions are indeed very costly, a major problem seems to be that clients and justice providers do not succeed in concluding suitable justice transactions. D. Transaction Costs of Justice Services Justice can only reach a plaintiff if there is a provider of justice services who is motivated to deliver suitable services to this plaintiff. Assuming these justice services cost less to produce than the value for the plaintiff, such transactions will take place, unless the costs of concluding the transaction are too high. Transaction costs analysis is usually applied to the broader economy. On the market for goods and services, buyers and sellers incur various costs of undertaking a transaction (Williamson 1981; Rao 2003). The parties have to search for suitable partners, inform themselves about the attributes of goods and services, and negotiate a contract. After the contract has been concluded, the buyer has to monitor the performance by the seller, and the seller has to ensure that the buyer pays the price. Transactions need some governance structure and this is costly to set up. Legal costs and other costs to resolve disputes are textbook examples of such transaction costs. Regulation of the market is sometimes necessary to prevent market failure, and where governments step in other rules are needed to diminish government failure. The costs of regulation, the costs of running the economic system, are also transaction costs. Legal advice, dispute resolution, and regulation are also services that have to be provided by people to other people, however. Plaintiffs conclude justice transactions with advisers, such as lawyers, and experts, or with neutrals, such as mediators, judges, neutral factfinders and arbiters. In the area of enforcement, police officers, bailiffs, and other government agents may have to be involved. On informal paths to justice, plaintiffs and defendants may consult friends, local leaders, and religious authorities. In case plaintiffs have to deal with powerful companies or individuals as defendants, they may have to convince other people with similar complaints to join the action. In order to put enough pressure on the defendant, thousands of people may have to join forces. These transactions can again be studied through the perspective of transaction costs. In a sense, this is thus a second order transaction cost problem. � � � Transaction costs of justice services include again the costs of information about suitable providers of justice services, the search costs, and the costs of negotiating the transaction (Rao 2003). For instance, a plaintiff will have to explain his problem to the lawyer, and the lawyer will have to decide on which conditions he will take the case. If a local leader is addressed, he will also hear the plaintiff, and then decide whether it is worthwhile for him to help the plaintiff. After the plaintiff has reached agreement with the provider of justice services that he will take some action, the plaintiff has to monitor the service provider and see to it that he delivers what he promised (Williamson 1981; Williamson 2005). Another type of transaction costs are the costs of running the part of the economic system that delivers justice services, These costs include the costs of coping with market failure and government failure. Market failure may arise from public goods, externalities, incomplete markets, and incomplete information. Government failure may also be caused by limited information, as well as by limited control over private market response, over bureaucracy, or over the political process (Stiglitz 2000). Each way of organizing transactions, either through the market or through goverments, has its costs and the challenge is to minimize these costs (Williamson 1999; Rao 2003; Brousseau and Raynaud 2006). Table 2 gives an overview of transaction cost problems that are likely to occur in justice markets (Barendrecht 2009). Each of the five types of dispute resolution services that a plaintiff needs, has its own characteristics that lead to certain transaction cost problems. Three transaction cost problems are most salient in these five justice markets. First, buying dispute services is difficult because two opponents are unlikely to agree on the kind of service they need. Disputants may experience psychological barriers that make it difficult to enter a cooperative procedure and often also have strategic reasons for not agreeing on a procedure. These coordination problems persist during the dispute resolution process. When courts or other neutrals decide disputes, they thus experience insufficient incentives from their clients to supply high quality and low cost procedures. A second source of high transaction costs is that dispute services partly consist of providing expertise. Such information tends to be difficult to sell for a profit because of its public good character. As a consequence, conflict management skills (integrative negotiation know how), objective criteria for settling distributive issues, and relationship formats (contracts) do not always reach the persons that need them most. Third, justice transactions tend to have a higher value if other justice transactions are also available. Negotiation assistance and neutral decision making by courts, for instance, work better if objective criteria for settling distributive issues are available. The incentives on defendants to solve conflicts cooperatively and to live up to outcomes typically come from the joint effects of monitoring, the value of reputation, the threat of informal sanctions, internal motivation, and formal enforcement. Many people have to cooperate to make this happen. These complementarities, network-effects, or connected transactions require an integrated approach (Barendrecht 2009). These major sources of transaction costs explain several important characteristics of justice markets. Although it would generally be most efficient if two disputing parties would consult one neutral agent, such transactions with mediators or arbiters are unlikely to occur. Instead, the parties tend to go to unilateral advisers, such as lawyers. Because the market for neutral assistance is likely to fail, the state steps in with a procedure in which the defendant is obliged to appear before a court. Transaction cost analysis also explains why legal services tend to be individualized. This is a business model that circumvents the public good character of information. Negotiation skills, conflict management know how, and knowledge about norms for distributive issues is hard to sell for a profit, because it can spread freely to other customers once it is sold. Furthermore, ���� � legal uncertainty is likely to occur: the market will not produce sufficient objective criteria for settling distributive issues. Finally, litigation and other forms of adjudication tend to be inefficient, because plaintiff and defendant are unlikely to agree on a procedure, and because of the connectedness between different justice services. Tasks Basic technology Sources of Transaction Costs Market reactions 1. Meet Make costs and benefits of participation for defendant higher than costs and benefits of fighting, or avoiding 1. Difficulties of concluding ex post dispute resolution agreements: - Psychological barriers - Strategic barriers 2. Cooperation between many people needed to organize sufficient incentives on powerful defendants to cooperate 1. Little demand for mediation, arbitration, and other tailor made neutral dispute services 2. Unilateral advice where neutral services would be more efficient 3. Demand for patronage (help from people who can influence the defendant) 4. Demand for checks and balances 2.Talk Support integrative negotiation (interest based) Information about negotiation and conflict management is public good 1. Insufficient supply 2. Business models for delivering expertise: - individualized advice - coaching client through process - taking over process from client - packaging information 3. Share Supply information about fair shares (sharing rules, objective criteria) 1. Information about fair solutions is public good 2. Providers of fairness information face pressure/criticism from all sides 1. Insufficient supply 2. Business models for delivering expertise (see above) 4. Decide Make option of a neutral decision available (at low cost) 1. Difficulties of concluding ex post dispute resolution agreements: - Psychological barriers - Strategic barriers 2. Insufficient incentives on neutral to provide efficient processes and fair solutions because of: - dependence on neutral - low frequency of transactions - uncertainty and complexity - monitoring difficulties. 1. Access to neutrals on markets is unavailable or unreliable 2. States provide neutrals 5. Stabilize Supply tools to make arrangements explicit; Make costs and benefits of compliance higher than those of non-compliance Information about contracting and making relationships transparent is public good Cooperation between many people needed to organize sufficient incentives on powerful defendants to cooperate 1. Insufficient supply 2. Business models for delivering expertise 3. Lack of enforcement, in particular against powerful defendants Supply Chain Approach Strengthen links between tasks Complementarities/connectedness between the five types of services Integrated business models for providing unilateral legal services, mediation and adjudication Table 2: Sources of Transaction Costs on Markets for Justice and Ways Markets Cope with Them (Barendrecht 2009) The following five sections explore how government interventions in the justice sector react to these transaction cost problems. For each of the five types of justice services, I first give an impression of the structure of the market. I describe the basic technology, discuss some best practices for delivering the services, and identify justice providers that are active on this market. Then, I summarize the transaction costs problems that occur on this market (Subsection A)? Next, current justice policies are discussed, taking their potential to diminish transaction costs as a criterion for evaluation (Subsection B). As many of these policies not seem to address these problems squarely, Subsection C identifies alternative justice policies that tackle the problems of transaction costs more directly, and that thus may be more promising. ���� � III. Letting Disputants Enter a Cooperative Procedure A. Market Analysis Managing a conflict in a cooperative way requires interaction between parties. A procedure or negotiation is unthinkable without some kind of information exchange (Shariff 2003). The parties require some kind of process where both of them are present and willing to communicate about the conflict: a room, or a tree under which to talk; written communication channels, or a webinterface. The first challenge for a plaintiff is to tempt the defendant to come to such a meeting place. The basic technology for letting the defendant (and the plaintiff) participate in cooperative dispute resolution is to make the costs and benefits of participation higher than the costs alternatives, such as fighting or avoiding the other party. The meeting place can be made attractive by being safe, close (low travelling costs), and giving the prospect of a solution with high value for the defendant. Letting disputants meet in order to solve a dispute cooperatively is difficult, Psychologically, one or both of the parties may suffer from loss aversion or overoptimism, and emotionally it may be hard to face the other party again. The parties may distrust the proposal of the other party to solve the conflict in a particular procedure, a phenomenon called reactive devaluation (Ross 1995; Barendrecht and De Vries 2006). Strategically it can be more attractive for the parties to avoid or postpone meeting, especially for a defendant who is better of now than he expects to be after resolution of the dispute. Landes and Posner called this the “submission problem” in the context of letting the disputants chosing a private judge (Landes and Posner 1979). Theoretically, a transaction aimed at solving the dispute through mutually agreed upon methods poses a bargaining problem. By agreeing on the procedure, the parties influence the outcome of the dispute (see, for the distributional effects of agreeing about institutions in general, Knight 1992). Bargaining failure is likely, because parties tend to do better if they take extreme positions, commit to earlier offers, or use delaying tactics (Muthoo 1999; Muthoo 2000; Mnookin 2003; Barendrecht 2009). The high transaction costs of concluding an agreement over the way to resolve a dispute have a major impact on the market for dispute services. They are probably the most significant reason why state interventions in this market are needed. If it was easy to solve disputes simply by buying dispute services, governments would probably not set up courts and legal procedures. Moreover, this transaction costs problem causes serious trouble on the market for alternative dispute resolution. Mediation and arbitration services are widely available, but demand for it is negligible, because it requires two parties who jointly decide to contract such a third party, which is unlikely to happen in case of a dispute (Barendrecht and De Vries 2006; Barendrecht 2009; Velikonja 2009). On the micro-level, plaintiffs respond to this problem in two different ways. These reactions create a lively market for unilateral legal advice, as well as an even more interesting demand for powerful ‘neutrals’ that can influence the defendant. These transactions are complicated and make life not always easier for the plaintiff. An agent such as a lawyer is in a slightly better position to solve a problem of how to meet with the opposing party than the client himself (Mnookin, Susskind et al. 1999). He may be more skilled in contacting the other party and inducing her to cooperate, as well as being less emotional and thus avoiding some psychological barriers to conflict resolution. But he cannot reduce reactive devaluation, over-optimism and loss aversion if he contacts the other party as an agent for the plaintiff. The strategic barriers to reaching an agreement over the dispute resolution process do not diminish because the agent is ���� � present. With a lawyer, it is still difficult to solve the second order bargaining problem. In this “second” dispute, over the way to solve the “first” dispute, the parties are still likely to put forward extreme offers, use delaying tactics, and commit themselves to positions. In many countries, the major reason a plaintiff uses a lawyer is probably that he is the one who can activate the court system. Hiring a lawyer may signal that court action is imminent, making the threat of court action more credible. But concluding a transaction with a lawyer also creates new transaction cost problems: How to incentivize him to obtain a speedy and high value solution to the dispute? How to prevent an arms race where both lawyers invest more and more in winning the dispute, creating work for each other? And a lawyer is most effective if he can threaten with a neutral intervention, which may be unavailable. An alternative for the plaintiff is to go to a person who can influence the defendant. People look for parents, bosses, clan leaders and government officials who can help them to get their way in relationships with others. Asking the powerful for help can be also be seen as a transaction. The powerful person offers his interventions, which will cost him an effort, and will probably want something in return: cash, support for his causes, or an increased reputation. The transactions between plaintiffs and powerful third parties have high transaction costs, because influencing a defendant is a highly context specific task, which is difficult to monitor. Moreover, the defendant may be influenced in a way that is undesirable. Therefore the demand for interventions from the powerful creates an additional demand for checks and balances on power. Task 1. Meet Description Centralized forum for information processing in which both parties participate Basic technology Make costs and benefits of participation for defendant higher than costs and benefits of alternatives such as fighting, or avoiding Best practices for dispute services/-transactions - Local meeting places or other channels of communication - Pre-mediation skills - Social norms to solve conflicts cooperatively - Enhance incentives that link to reputation of defendants to solve conflicts cooperatively - Option of default judgment Possible providers of services - First line legal aid (paralegals) - Friends and advisers - Community leaders - Mediators - Courts Sources of Transaction costs 1. Difficulties of concluding ex post dispute resolution agreements: - Psychological barriers - Strategic barriers (bargaining failure) 2. Cooperation between many people needed to organize sufficient incentives on powerful defendants to cooperate Market reactions 1. Little demand for mediation, arbitration, and other tailor made neutral dispute services 2. Unilateral advice where neutral services would be more efficient 3. Demand for patronage (help from people who can influence the defendant) 4. Demand for checks and balances Table 3 Market Analysis for Services that Assist Disputants with Meeting A third way to cope with the high transaction costs of meeting is to agree on a dispute resolution mechanism before a conflict arises (Landes and Posner 1979). Business partners, for instance, sometimes put an arbitration clause in their contracts. More complex dispute resolution agreements may provide for several stages of dispute management, prescribing first negotiations between the parties, followed by mediation, and, as a last resort, arbitration. Ex ante dispute resolution agreements work because the psychological barriers of reactive devaluation, loss aversion, and over-optimism are less prominent at the time the parties conclude a contract. As long as there is no actual conflict, the risk of bargaining failure regarding a conflict resolution clause is also lower. Both parties generally wish to ���� � minimize the costs of future conflict in their relationship, so they are quite likely to agree on a way to resolve possible disputes. Most agreements about a way to resolve future disputes are part of a contractual arrangement. This formalization process does not take place in many relationships, though. Most family, business, land use or neighbour relationships are not made explicit in a contract. Tort claims or claims against governments are seldom preceded by a contractual arrangement. Even if a written contract is reached, this opportunity to choose a dispute mechanism is not always used. Eisenberg and Miller found that only 20% of contracts between sophisticated business partners contained a dispute resolution clause (Eisenberg and Miller 2006). Often, one of the parties takes up the formalization process that produces dispute resolution clauses. Employers write employment contracts. Sellers and building contractors refer consumer disputes and building disputes to specialized neutrals. The problem with dispute resolution clauses in adhesion contracts is that there can be serious doubts regarding neutrality. Plaintiffs may be excluded from using litigation mechanisms that they wanted to use after the conflict arose, or may be confronted with an arbitrator who depends on a constant stream of cases from the defendant. These worries translate into an extensive debate, continuing before the courts, on whether arbitration clauses in adhesion contracts should be allowed or not (Ware 2004; Sternlight 2005; Brunet, Speidel et al. 2006; Sternlight 2007). B. Current Interventions by States The stage is set. High transaction costs of agreeing to meet and solve a dispute cooperatively shape the markets for justice. Plaintiffs go to unilateral advisers (lawyers), or to powerful peopls who can influence the defendant, unless they have concluded an ex ante dispute agreement, but that is unlikely. Let us now see how governments intervene in this area. Do they tackle the problem that two people in a dispute cannot agree on a suitable way to manage the dispute? Are these policies effective in reducing the transaction costs of such an agreement? 1. Reducing the Rewards of Continued Conflict An indirect response to the high transaction costs of meeting is to make other ways of solving conflicts, such as fighting, less attractive. Societies have social norms and legal rules that prohibit the use of violence by citizens. Besides lowering the costs of conflict, such rules make fighting less attractive as a way to solve the conflict. Cooperation thus becomes more likely (Hirshleifer 2000; Hirshleifer 2001; Posner 2003). Restraints on using some technologies of conflict, such as strikes or employee lock-out in labour conflicts, also makes cooperation more likely (Posner 2003) However, these policies do not diminish the transaction costs of meeting. They do not lower the psychological and strategical barriers to starting a negotiation process and jointly deciding on a procedure to cope with the conflict. Moreover, strategies that use other forms of power, such as threats to withhold essential goods to the other party (access to water, food, economic opportunities, or protection), are not affected by these rules. So powerful defendants still have many other options than sitting down with the plaintiff to reach a fair solution. 2. Judgments by Default Societies also developed procedures in which the defendant is forced to meet with the plaintiff. If he does not cooperate in the procedure by putting forward his views on the conflict when summoned, a default judgment will be issued against him. The basis for this judgment by default is usually the point of view of the plaintiff. So the decision will generally be unfavourable for the defendant, giving him a powerful incentive to ���� � cooperate. Ultimately, a defendant has to talk to the court, and thus it is more sensible for him to talk about the conflict with the plaintiff prior to that occasion. We should note, however, that this incentive to meet and talk only works if a plaintiff can credibly threaten to take the defendant to court. Poor plaintiffs may not be able to do this, especially if defendants know that they do not have the resources to sit through a civil court procedure. For governments, the costs of organizing a court system that is able to guarantee enforceable default judgments are substantial. A similar problem regarding access to a neutral decision may arise for public law enforcement. The administrative and other costs of criminal prosecution may be so high that the threat of an orderly criminal procedure is not credible anymore. Police officers, who can be seen as the plaintiffs in these procedures, may then choose to neglect crime, or resort to violence to fight it, because these options become a more attractive alternative for them. Finally, the incentive of a default judgment is still indirect. It is an incentive to appear in court and defend oneself against an accusation. In order to avoid this procedure, some defendants prefer to try settlement negotiations. There is no direct obligation to participate in such negotiations. 3. Stimulating Mediation and Arbitration Lately, governments have started to promote mediation as a way to solve legal disputes. Mediators have been trained and mediation programs have been set up. For international conflicts, diplomats from many countries are available to facilitate talks between the parties. Unfortunately, merely offering these services does not seem to substantially help in bringing disputants to the negotiating table. Mediation is hyped, but it solves a negligible proportion of disputes. Its main source of survival after 30 years of experimentation in the US and Europe is as an add-on to courts (Goldberg and Shaw 2007; Velikonja 2009). In court annexed mediation, judges refer some of their cases to mediation. Ex post mediation, agreed directly between the parties without a contract or a neutral person telling them they have to mediate, is still the exception. The same is true for arbitration (Landes and Posner 1979). Our analysis strongly suggests that the cause of this problem is not an insufficient supply of low cost mediation and arbitration services. In fact, helping other people to solve their disputes is psychologically rewarding work and many mediators offer their services. Mediation is also good value for money. Mediation services attract high satisfaction ratings and big majorities of users say they will use it again in future conflicts (Wall, Stark et al. 2001; Wissler 2004; Wall Jr and Chan-Serafin 2009). It is not, however, an answer to the high transaction costs of meeting, the psychological barriers to agreeing on a process to solve the conflict, nor the strategic barriers that are likely to lead to bargaining failure influenced by making mediation available. It is easy to see how the availability of mediation only tips the balance in favour of going to the meeting place in a limited category of cases. For the defendant, it makes meeting and talking a bit more attractive because it creates a friendly and private environment to discuss issues. Availability of mediation services at the meeting place also influences the expected outcome because the parties may then be able to create more value. If the parties already want to cooperate, it thus helps them. But availabilty of mediation does not really change the way value will be distributed. If the dispute is (mostly) about distributing value, and a neutral decision is not available for a reasonable price so that the expected outcome is still low for the plaintiff, mediation services are not likely to make a real difference and the plaintiff will not find it very ���� � attractive. In the words of Hazel Genn, one of the leading experts on mediation: “Mediation without a credible threat of judicial determination is the sound of one hand clapping” (Genn 2008). For the defendant, if his goal is to extract as much value from the distributive issues as possible, mediation services are not very interesting either. At the mediation table, he cannot as easily use delaying tactics, make extreme offers, commit to earlier offers, or hide information, although these are the strategies that lead to the best results in distibutive bargaining. As we will see in Section VII where complementarities are discussed, mediation services are far more valuable for both parties if they are delivered in the shadow of an easily accessible neutral decision. C. Promising Policies We discussed three government policies (prohibiting violence, threatening to issue default judgments, and making mediation available) that indirectly stimulate the parties in a conflict to meet. These policies do not directly tackle the problem, however. They do not lower the costs of jointly determining a way to solve the conflict. There may be policies or market solutions that make it easier to agree about a process to solve a conflict. 1. Social Norms and Unilateral Pledges to Deal with Conflict Cooperatively One such policy is instilling a social norm, or even imposing a legal rule, that parties in a conflict should meet and talk. If they cannot solve the conflict through negotiation, they should at least look for a process to solve the conflict, or to cope with it in a way that minimizes difficulties. That can be felt as an obligation. Social norms about the ways to deal with conflict exist in many cultures, communities, and organizations. Collectivist cultures tend to stress the need for harmony, and have less tolerance for other strategies such as fighting. Mediation by third parties is stimulated by social norms in many Asian countries (Wall, Stark et al. 2001). Chinese conflict management embodies “a culture of three”, in which it is preferred to have a third party present above solving conflicts in direct, confrontational negotiations. The third party can help persons with status to loose face, avoid the assertiveness necessary in direct conflict negotiations, help disputants to cope with emotions, and restore harmony (Jia 2002). Legal norms to meet and talk also exist. Many bar associations have at least a nominal rule that requires lawyers to attempt settlement before they bring a case to court. Conflict between employees and employers can be reduced by allowing employees and employer to organize themselves, and creating a setting in which they will trust each and negotiate (Posner 2003). A unilateral pledge to cooperatively solve conflicts is a possibility as well. The CPR pledge has been accepted by a number of U.S. companies. This policy statement obliges subscribing companies to seriously explore ADR in cases with other signatories before pursuing full-scale litigation. Such a pledge reduces the probability of bargaining failure regarding a way to process the conflict. Likewise, a government agency can commit itself to resolving disputes with citizens through direct and informal communication, and, if necessary, to negotiations assisted by a mediator. 2. Opening the Market for Neutral Dispute Resolution Services As we have seen, lawyers acting unilaterally for one of the parties may contribute to the dispute resolution process. This, however, has costs: clients and lawyers have dissimilar interests, and invoking lawyers increases the possibility of an arms race. Lawyers add additional levels of communication and thus complexity (Mnookin, Susskind et al. 1999). Folk wisdom is that lawyers are sometimes necessary, but should be avoided whenever possible. Lawyer services can be developed, however, that are less likely to increase transaction costs (Lande 2005; Lande 2008). Lawyers may empower the client to meet and talk, ���� � lowering the costs of confrontation for him, if they work as a coach, staying in the background, helping the client to communicate and negotiate. Another possibility is to let a neutral person set up a pre-mediation process, in which the option of making an agreement about a way to cope with the conflict is discussed with both parties. Paralegals and other first line legal aid providers often try to contact the other party on behalf of their clients in order to get the communication going. Facilitation of meeting may help to overcome the second order bargaining problem in similar ways as a mediator may help to overcome the first order bargaining problem. There is little research, however, on the effectiveness of these first line interventions, and also little descriptive work regarding the best practices for nurturing these initial contacts between disputants (see Moore 2003 for some possible interventions). One step further is the development of neutral dispute resolution services that integrate this first phase. The plaintiff goes directly to a neutral dispute resolution provider. This person commits himself to the plaintiff to facilitate a transparent process that leads to a fair outcome against reasonable cost, not to maximize the plaintiff’s outcome. If a client comes with a problem, the consultation can be about the possible views from both sides, about ways to solve the problem, and about neutral criteria that may be applicable. The facilitator establishes contact with the defendant and invites him to participate, giving him the same commitment to process and a fair outcome. If the defendant does not participate, the process continues without him and creates reasonable incentives for the defendant to live up to the outcome that results from the process (see Barendrecht 2009 for an exploration of this approach). Although they have not yet been tested extensively, it is likely that these approaches can lower the transaction costs of meeting. Reactive devaluation is less likely, particularly if it is not the opponent but a neutral who proposes a suitable dispute resolution procedure. A neutral, who is generally less susceptible to negative emotions, may also be able to reduce over-optimism as to what will happen if the conflict remains unresolved. He may also reduce the probability of bargaining failure, as he can facilitate information exchange. But other problems may emerge. It remains to be seen whether these more neutral dispute resolution services can develop into a sustainable business model. Not only does a neutral have two clients that may not be on speaking terms, she has to secure payment of her fees from both of them. Although more neutral models are frequently practiced by lawyers, they are not yet emphasized in legal education. Regulation of lawyers tends to stress the unilateral model. And non-lawyers, who may have the necessary coaching skills, often do not have access to the market for such services because of the tight regulation of the legal profession in many countries (Stephen and Love 1999). Even if neutral legal advice in conflicts is permitted, one-sided legal advice may still be the norm in the legal profession. 3. Regulating Ex Ante Dispute Resolution Agreements As we saw, ex ante dispute resolution agreements are a good tool to lower transaction costs. Regulation of such clauses can be an important contribution to increasing their acceptability, and to prevent abuse of ADR. Several authors have suggested criteria that make ADR clauses more acceptable, which are sometimes already part of legislation or case law (Welsh 2004). Making them binding for the (powerful) party who wrote the clause and not for the (less powerful) consumer or employee (Sternlight 2007) is one option. Criteria as to the acceptability of waiving punitive damages claims, extensive discovery, or participation in class actions are important as well. On the positive side, criteria can be formulated that guarantee procedural quality, outcome fairness, and low cost access to justice. ���� � Most of the scholarly discussion focuses on arbitration clauses, mediation clauses, and jurisdiction clauses when choosing a particular court for dealing with disputes. Dispute resolution agreements, however, can be more sophisticated than that. They may stipulate that the parties will first consult with each other in case of a dispute. If they do not agree on substance, they can agree that they will search for a procedure. If they still cannot agree, the clause can tell them to ask a third party to determine the procedure, for which they can set some criteria beforehand. 4. Requiring Repeat-Players to Offer an Accessible Dispute System A more active regulation policy is to require an organization to have a suitable dispute resolution mechanism in place (O Shea and Rickett 2006). Financial services regulators and telecom regulators have started to require an effective dispute resolution mechanism as a condition for being given a license to operate in the consumer market. Interestingly, companies facilitating consumer markets make similar moves. The “Square Trade” dispute resolution process is mandatory for eBay sellers. Trade organizations sometimes also require that a member lets his disputes be resolved by a private dispute resolution mechanism. Such policies can be extended to other areas where repeat-players regularly have disputes with users of their products or services. Government agencies, companies serving a certain number of customers yearly, and employers with a certain number of employees could be required to have a dispute resolution system in place that is of sufficient quality and offers low cost access to justice. If these dispute resolution schemes are adequately monitored (against criteria such as the ones discussed in the preceding paragraph), they may be a powerful way to increase access to justice. This is particularly true if the consumer or employee can opt out and choose to use a court action instead (Sternlight 2007). 5. Co-opting Powerful Defendants The biggest threat to a dispute system is that a powerful defendant has insufficient reasons to cooperate. An extreme example of this is a dictator who has committed atrocities in the past and is now an obstacle to lasting peace and economic development. Somehow, the costs of not cooperating have to be increased for him, and the benefits of cooperating as well. But why would he cooperate in the future if he can expect to be severely punished for what he did in the past? It may be necessary to co-opt him by granting him some form of immunity. Prosecution of heads of state, as is now taking place before the International Criminal Court, may be a good idea in order to prevent future harm, but it is also an obstacle to peaceful resolution of conflict as it raises the costs of cooperation for dictators. This setting is not unique for the international arena. Employers using unfair employment conditions and husbands committing domestic violence face a similar trade-off. For them, cooperation may be too threatening because sanctions loom large. The solution can be found in two directions. The costs of non-cooperation can be raised by increasing the likelihood of sanctions, such as the use of force against dictators, or other perpetrators. If a government has the resources to bring every perpetrator to justice, to conduct a trial, and to inflict costly punishment, this resolution can be a sustainable policy. Lowering the costs of cooperation for perpetrators can be another road to a peaceful settlement of conflict. This is the realm of transitional justice (Mani 2005). Truth and reconciliation commissions, like the ones used in South Africa and many other post- conflict situations, may not meet everyone’s taste for justice. Economically, they make sense though. Cooperation is made more attractive for those who cooperate, in manners such as telling the truth, by granting them immunity from sanctions. For the victims of the �� � � crimes committed by the apartheid regime, this process, which can lead to apologies and reconciliation, may or may not be the optimal outcome. However, this way to induce defendants to meet and talk can be preferable, because the expected outcome for the victims is still better than the alternatives, including the possibility of getting no justice at all, or of a civil war that would destroy many opportunities for joint gains in the future (Lie et al. 2007). The same reasoning applies to disputes between individuals. Informal justice mechanisms in developing economies, which have to operate in situations with low levels of enforcement, tend to concentrate on reconciliation, even in cases of severe crimes (Quinn 2005). The broader message is probably this: In situations of unequal power which cannot be restrained by government action (and this is often where the need for justice is biggest!), a dispute system that promises completely neutral and fair justice for all participants is likely to be ineffective. It will not be used, in particular, if costly retribution is part of it. Hence, only the second best solutions may be feasible, in which the outcomes are unambiguous improvements of the position of the less powerful parties, but not ‘perfect justice.’ This settling for second best justice is not for eternity, however. The cycle of creating stability, new challenges, and coping with conflict can start once again. In several rounds of improvements, which may take many years, it is possible to move gradually towards a truly satisfactory situation. IV. The Market for Negotiation Assistance A. Market Analysis Once he has succeeded in opening communication channels, the next service a plaintiff needs is assistance in the negotiations that will take place. The basic technology for this is generally described in the literature as integrative – or problemsolving – negotiations (Walton and McKersie 1965; Fisher, Ury et al. 1991; Lewicki, Saunders et al. 2006). This well developed technology supports negotiations by creating an environment that promotes communication and information-sharing, reviewing and adjusting perceptions. In these processes, the focus is on the needs, wishes and fears of the disputants. Integrative negotiations are interest based. The disputants are advised to take a joint problem-solving approach to the dispute, be creative in developing a number of solutions, and choose a (win-win) solution that best fits the interests of both parties. Skills and practices that support these processes are described in the literature and tested to some extent as well (Wall, Stark et al. 2001; Moffitt, Bordone et al. 2005; Deutsch, Coleman et al. 2006; Oetzel and Ting-Toomey 2006; Wall Jr and Chan-Serafin 2009). Task 2. Talk Description Communication and negotiation Basic technology Support integrative negotiation (problemsolving, interest based) Best practices for dispute services/-transactions - Negotiation assistance (integrative negotiations) - Communication, active listening, questioning techniques - Reframing and adjusting perceptions - Managing emotions and interaction - Improving relationship, recognition, apology, supply of coping skills - Standard formats for integrative negotiations (identify interests, issues, explore win-win solutions) Possible providers of services - Advisers - Lawyers - Mediators (facilitative) - On-line facilities Sources of Transaction costs Information about negotiation techniques and conflict management is public good and experience good Market reactions 1. Insufficient supply 2. Business models for delivering expertise: - individualized advice - coaching client through process - taking over process from client - packaging information Table 4 Market Analysis for Services that Assist Disputants with Talking �� � � Transactions in which the parties buy these services can be concluded with friends or family members who happen to have these skills. Professional mediators, (cooperative) lawyers, and perhaps even with online dispute resolution providers can supply them as well (Katsh, Katsh et al. 2001; Wall, Stark et al. 2001; Moore 2003; Lande 2005; Lande 2008). In an ideal world, people in a conflict could learn these skills cheaply, or they could be coached by a professional who helps leads them through the communication and negotiation process. Such services have trouble to reach customers with limited resources, though. Assistance with resolving a conflict using the techniques and skills of integrative negotiations basically consists of delivering expertise. Markets for such information goods are special, because information is a public good (it is difficult to exclude people from using it once it is supplied), an experience good (the quality of the information can only be assessed by the customer after delivery) and the upfront production costs of the information are high in comparison to the marginal costs of producing an extra copy and distributing it (Varian 1998; Stiglitz 1999). If a professional just teaches his clients how to communicate and negotiate, he will soon be out of business, because clients can spread this information freely, and are likely to be unwilling to pay for the information upfront. Thus, the transaction costs on this market are substantial and providers of conflict management skills have to find ways around it. Like other professional services firms, lawyers typically sell services that are customized and individualized. Often they combine delivery of information with other work, such as conducting negotiations for clients (instead of just coaching them) or litigation. These business models diminish the possibility for clients to reuse or to resell the information (Dawson 2005). However, these mixed and individual services tend to be expensive for the client. Hiring an individual expert such as a professional lawyer for the maybe ten hours that are needed to negotiate a simple dispute is too costly for most individuals. Dispute resolution services, like other knowledge products usually delivered by professional services firms, easily become a luxury good. B. Current Interventions by States Gradually, we now gain an understanding of the market for justice, using transaction costs analysis and knowing about the newest technologies for solving disputes, including the technology of integrative negotiations that dates from the 1960’s and became a mainstream part of conflict management in the 1980’s. But governments had to put dispute systems in place long before that. Their systems for coping with conflicts developed over the centuries. They had to cope with the effects of the transaction costs problems, lacking an understanding about the causes of these problems, and with limited knowledge about ways to solve conflict. What societies experienced, was a substantial number of disputes, an apparent unwillingness of disputants to meet and talk about these disputes, and a tendency of disputants to go to unilateral advisers or powerful people. The broader message they probably picked up was that many people are not able to solve their problem through negotiations. Somehow, the decisions have to be made for them. So governments resorted to norms and to decision makers with undisputed authority. 1. Framing Disputes in Terms of Rights and Obligations What gradually emerged in most societies is the procedure of resolving disputes in terms of who is right or wrong. If a conflict continues, a party can bring forward a claim that his rights were infringed on, and the other party can present a defence. The dispute is thus discussed in terms of rights and obligations. If this discussion does not lead to a result, a neutral third party has to decide for them. Thus, courts of law have to be established. This rights and obligations approach is attractive. It can build on moral categories and social norms about what good conduct is, which may come from religious sources. For a ���� � functioning market economy, it is very important that people live up to their contractual promises. So contractual rights and obligations are added to the norms that courts can enforce. Moreover, the moral duties as well as the norms related to enforcement of property rights and contracts can be applied generally, so that similar cases can be treated alike. They can also be used to reign in the powerful third parties who are asked to intervene in conflicts. Their power becomes less absolute, if they are bound by the rule of law. Reframing disputes in terms of rights and obligations also has several disadvantages. The legal framework does not necessarily fit the perceptions of clients. Many researchers have established that clients addressing the formal legal system feel that their needs are not sufficiently taken into account and experience a loss of control, which is commonly attributed to the selection effects of viewing social conflicts through a legal lense (see Relis 2002 for an extensive review of the literature). Morover, invoking a right and accusing a person that he has committed a wrong easily leads to polarization. It implies moral superiority of one party over the other, which is likely to lead to denial, or defensiveness. In disputes, the parties are very sensitive to being treated like other persons, and with all due respect. They use the way they are treated as a cue for their social status (Lind and Tyler 1988; Tyler 2007). The dynamics of accusing and excusing can be very troublesome in dispute resolution (Allred 2005). Escalation of conflicts is often the consequence of using this framework of rights and obligations. Another complication is that many conflicts are hard to solve on the basis of pre-existing duties that have not been fulfilled. As we saw, conflict is inherent to long term relationships with high specific investments, where it is caused by changes in circumstances that the parties cannot regulate completely in their contracts. Problems between business partners or family members are thus hard to resolve on the basis of right and wrong. Judging these conflicts on the basis of rights and obligations does not go well with the idea of an incomplete contract. And even in one time transactions, most disputes have other causes than pure opportunism. Most people know quite well that they have to pay for what they order and should deliver goods of appropriate quality, and have sufficient reasons to do so. The basis of contractual disputes is often a misunderstanding, or unhelpful communication at the time the problems came up. Even for major crimes, framing the issues in terms of rights and obligations is unlikely to do the job. Victims of crime have other needs besides a desire for punishment. They would like to be informed, to be offered an explanation, and to see their harm repaired. Finally, the confrontation creates an additional need for unilateral advice. Now, people not only need a trusted adviser who can coach them in difficult times, but also someone who can inform them about their rights and obligations. The need for a lawyer is increased. Solving conflicts through a system of rights and obligations is thus a mixed blessing. It fits moral categories, reinforces norms of desired behaviour, and prevents abuse of power to some extent. But it also raises the costs of dealing with disputes because it increases the possibility of escalation and impasse, leads to much uncertainty because many real life disputes are hard to solve by applying pre-existing norms, and creates an extra need for legal expertise. 2. Legal Aid Thus it is not surprising that governments resort to another common justice policy. They supply conflict management expertise to the poor who cannot afford it, and because the government dispute resolution system is based on rights and obligations, this is considered legal expertise. Most governments supply subsidized legal aid, or stimulate lawyers to do pro bono legal work. Some other models developed as well, such as the ���� � use of public defenders, in which government agencies provide legal aid in criminal cases. These policies are troublesome, however, because subsidizing legal aid given on a one lawyer to one client basis is a very expensive way to get conflict management know-how to the parties (Pearce 2004). Most states only offer legal aid to defendants in criminal cases facing severe sentences, and in a restricted manner to some plaintiffs in civil cases. Only a few countries have broad programs for legal aid in civil and administrative cases. More fundamentally, legal aid exacerbates the problems associated to unilateral advice, such as the possibility of an arms race between the parties (Pearce 2004). Giving the poor legal aid will not bring them equal access to justice if their richer counterparts can afford better lawyers. 3. Mediation Aid More recently, governments have started to subsidize mediation. In theory, this is an attractive approach because one mediator can replace two lawyers, and the problems with unilateral advice are avoided. Mediation also applies the method of integrative negotiations. These policies typically have little impact, however, for the reasons discussed earlier. The problem of letting two opponents agree on one mediator remains unsolved, whereas a party to a dispute can engage a lawyer without consulting her opponent. Moreover, mediation does not really fit the rest of the formal dispute resolution system that has been built on enforcing rights and obligations. Procedures, legal education, professional norms, business models, and the social norms of lawyers are all based on this model. So mediation is embedded in practices where lawyers do an intake with their clients focussed on rights and obligations, where they negotiate on this basis, and where courts interprete legal norms in order to decide conflicts in which mediations failed. Conflict management, and in particular the way to support integrative negotiations, is a new technology, which basically changed the way in which negotiations can be structured. Before that, the world just had to accept that some disputants do not communicate. With this new technology, up to 90% of people in a conflict can communicate and negotiate in order to improve their relationship, and around two thirds actually solve the dispute. If we take the long term view, it seems to be a disruptive technology, a paradigm change. But this new technology cannot take hold, unless the surrounding system also adapts to the new possibilities. Once a system of resolving disputes is based on a certain technology, the costs of changing this are likely to be huge, however. Resolving conflicts in terms of rights and obligations is a game everyone knows. Lawyers, courts, law schools and lawyers in the government form powerful interest groups. As collectives, they have little interest in changing the game, and individual lawyers cannot easily change it by themselves. New entrants in the market face barriers, such as the prohibition for non-lawyers to give legal advice in important markets like the U.S. and Germany. So, subsidizing and stimulating mediation is not likely to be a very successful justice policy in the short run. C. Promising Policies Instead, governments should rethink their interventions in the light of the new technical possibilities, but with a keen eye for transaction costs. Availability of conflict management know-how has made new ways of supporting negotiations possible. In the light of the new technology of integrative negotiations, government interventions in this part of the dispute resolution market may have become too broad. Before this conflict resolution technology developed, it was sensible to subsidize lawyers and to see neutral decisions by courts of law as the main way to let parties solve disputes. Now that we know that ���� � many issues in disputes can be solved by integrative negotiations, and the market can supply this, governments can target their interventions in a better way. Governments have already started to retreat. Trials and judgments by courts have become the exception, and settlement is the norm in civil disputes. Even in criminal cases, plea-bargaining has taken over. In the once considered very litigious US legal system, the trend has been named the ‘Vanishing Trial’ (Galanter 2004). But then what should governments supply instead? 1. Education in Integrative Negotiations and Conflict Management A promising approach can probably be found by directly confronting the major causes of transaction costs: the public good and experience good character of conflict management know-how. One way to spread this knowledge is through education programs, and this becomes an increasing part of the legal aid agenda. Non-formal legal education (Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor 2008), human rights education (Ramírez, Suárez et al. 2007), civic education (Davies 2004), or public legal education (Buck, Pleasence et al. 2008) are the terms under which this message is conveyed. Learning how to solve disputes, how to negotiate, and other relationship know-how seem to be valuable assets for anybody, but these skills are not taught at school in any formal way. NGOs in developing countries invest in teaching women and employees about their rights, and use a mixture of mass media, programs for schools, clinics, and paralegal services to spread the message (Penal Reform International and Bloom Legal Clinic of the Northwestern School of Law 2007; Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor 2008). Besides basic knowledge about law, these programs increasingly teach skills for coping with conflict, for instance in situations of domestic violence . The good news is that communication and negotiation skills are fairly general and can be used in most economic and personal relationships. A basic negotiation course can be taught in a week and this seems money well spent. Negotiation expertise is a public good that may have a big impact on human well-being if it were more universally available. Both economic growth and human development depend critically on how good people are in creating win-win relationships with other people and how they manage the disputes inside these relationships. The bad news is that the curriculum of schools and universities are full and belong to the kind of institutions that are most resistant to change. Slots in primary and secondary education are thus very difficult to obtain. In this respect, it is interesting to note that the theory and skills of integrative negotiations are not even an obligatory part of the curriculum in economics. Economists assume that wealth and welfare will be created by transactions, but do not study how transactions are formed. A more targeted approach is to spread this know-how to people who are likely to find themselves in the beginning stages of a conflict, or at key transitions in their lives (Buck, Pleasence et al. 2008). Some American states apply this principle by requiring that people complete a divorce course before they are admitted to a divorce procedure. Programs assisting women with dispute skills in order to cope with domestic violence have been linked to maternity care programs in developing countries (Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor 2008). 2. Economies of Scale in Communication and Negotiation Advice Once in a dispute, the parties must cope with the skills they have at that moment. Disputants may learn on the spot, but they will often need help with communicating and negotiating in a productive manner. The challenge is to bring this expertise to the negotiating table at a low cost, which means without having to pay one professional for exensive individualized dispute advice. ���� � The most promising approaches here are in the area of finding economies of scale. Legal expenses insurers have developed ways to serve many clients with similar problems by standardizing their services through protocols. Specialized dispute resolution services are offered by trade unions and consumer organizations to their members. Government outfits and law clinics at universities offer basic legal advice to people with legal problems. Paralegal programs are the most promising variant for developing economies (Maru 2006). Increasingly, legal advice is supported by internet interfaces, so that clients can start with self-help and then go onwards to personal advice if necessary. Advice can now be obtained by posting questions on the internet and obtaining answers in return for a fee. Websites that use this model include findlaw.com and lawguru.com. The question remains, however, whether this leads to viable business models for selling expertise. Like most IT companies, the providers struggle with keeping the balance between attracting many customers with free services and selling more sophisticated services for a fee. Most of these standardized services still have to integrate communication and negotiation advice into their offerings, however. The market still perceives the need as a legal need, and not so much as a need for knowing how to communicate and to negotiate (Hacker 2008). Governments can surely help to adjust this perception, which is caused by their prior interventions in this market. Because mechanisms for dispute resolution are widely perceived as a task for state institutions, the public is likely to appreciate some guidance from the government regarding the best ways to solve disputes. Public awareness programs regarding the way conflict management know how can be obtained are one way to achieve this. 3. Structuring Settlement Negotiations A more direct way to stimulate the use of modern conflict resolution know-how is to structure the communication in disputes along these lines. This is the modern equivalent of the rights and obligations approach. Instead of inviting people to frame their dispute in legal terms, the parties can be asked to communicate about their emotions and their needs, wishes and fears. Moreover, a government dispute system can ask them to bring forward a number of possible solutions and to suggest legal criteria and social norms for evaluation of these solutions, instead of requiring the plaintiff to formulate a claim and the defendant to submit all his possible defences. This negotiation support system could have the form of procedural rules, very similar to the codes of procedure, but now applicable to the negotiations that usually precede the court action. Other possibilities are to build a web-based negotiation support system, or to let interest groups come to a code of conduct for the settlement of claims (Van Zeeland, Kamminga et al. 2007). Again, a motive for this government intervention could be to compensate for the existing government incentives to frame a conflict (only) in terms of rights and obligations. Once such a framework is in place, the market can bring additional negotiation and communication skills to the table. As we have seen, there are many people around who wish to assist people with communication and negotiation, once they sit in a room and are ready to be helped. Mediators, other neutral facilitators, online dispute resolution services, collaborative lawyers, or more traditional lawyers can provide these services. Finding the people with the right skills is something disputants can sort out by themselves, probably with support from a little regulation that helps clients to distinguish good quality from bad quality, as is common in other professional services (Stephen and Love 1999). ���� � V. Supplying Information about Fair Solutions A. Market Analysis In disputes, the parties always have to cope with distributive issues. The parties must determine an amount of compensation, the length of a notice period, a way to divide assets which they jointly own, and sometimes the severity of a sanction. Bargaining in this situation of bilateral monopoly is likely to fail, because parties tend to obtain better results if they have more patience, make more extreme offers, commit themselves more, have more attractive outside and inside options, and have more information. (Muthoo 1999; Muthoo 2000; Carraro, Marchiori et al. 2006; Korobkin and Doherty 2007). This all amounts to uncooperative conduct. Consequently, the tension between creating value, for which cooperation and information sharing is most effective, and distributing value, where a unilateral strategy is usually more succesful, complicates the process of dispute resolution (Mnookin, Peppet et al. 2000). The only known way this bargaining failure can be prevented, is by bringing neutrality in the game. Information about the way other people have settled similar issues is one way to do provide a neutral point of view. Informing the parties about solutions reached in comparable situations helps them to assess the fairness of outcomes (Pillutla and Murnighan 2003; Husted and Folger 2004; Cialdini 2007). Market prices, rules of thumb used in practice, social norms, or case law can provide people with this information (Fisher, Ury et al. 1991; Shell 2006; Barendrecht and Verdonschot 2008; Verdonschot 2009). These ‘objective criteria’ create a shadow of the law, a neutral image of a just world, that the parties can use as a point of reference for reaching agreement (Mnookin and Kornhauser 1978; Cooter, Marks et al. 1982; Hacker 2008; Nisenbaum 2009; Ray 2009). People in a dispute tend to ask for these criteria: what did others get in my situation (Hacker 2008)? Task Share Description Distributing value fairly Basic technology Supply information about fair shares (sharing rules, objective criteria) Best practices for dispute services/-transactions - Bargaining assistance (distributive negotiations) - Objective norms and criteria for three/five most common issues in most common disputes that: o can be applied easily; o weigh similar elements for both; o give a continuous range of outcomes, not binary answers (yes/no); o belong to the parties (legitimacy, fairness, appropriateness); o allow for adjustment to situation: o are not exclusive; o show what others did in similar situations; Make this information widely available in order to increase transparency Possible providers of services - Advisers - Lawyers - Mediators (evaluative) - Legislators - Courts rendering precedents - Legal academics Legal information providers (publishers) Sources of Transaction costs 1. Information about fair solutions is public good and experience good 2. Providers of fairness information face pressure/criticism from all sides Market reactions 1. Insufficient supply 2. Business models for delivering expertise (see above) Table 5 Market Analysis for Services that Assist Disputants with Sharing Unfortunately, objective criteria are not always available (Barendrecht and Verdonschot 2008; Yeazell 2008). Information about the going rates of justice is costly to produce (Barendrecht 2009), because it requires extensive knowledge about the ways disputes of a certain type have been settled by the disputants or decided by neutrals. The information has the character of a public good: once the information is published, the marginal costs of letting another person use the information is close to zero, and it is very difficult to exclude people from using the information. To make things worse, the client can only know whether the information is valuable for him if the norms are disclosed to ���� � him first. But why should he pay upfront for a good that still has to prove its value? Because the production costs of this information are high, and it is a public good, as well as an ‘experience good’, there is little commercial incentive to produce rules regarding suitable ways to deal with distributive issues (Posner and Rasmusen 1999; Parisi 2000). To make things worse, the producer of distributive rules is unlikely to have many friends. Because of the natural tendency of people to be biased in the way they perceive fairness, producers of distributive norms are likely to be criticized from all sides. The market for legal expertise thus has similar characteristics as the one communication and negotiation know-how. Lawyers offer tailor made legal advice, and bundle legal information with other services, such as helping parties to write a contract or to argue a case in court. Legal information providers such as writers of handbooks and publishers of databases supply packages, in which procedural rules, rules of conduct put down in legislation and commentary are sold together with an occasional norm for settling distributive issues. If a plaintiff just wants to know what the usual criteria are for dividing assets in a divorce, for damages in a personall injury case, or for compensation if a second hand car has serious defects, there is often no place to go. B. Current Interventions by States The scarcity of public information about distributive issues is a problem that has been tackled by several government interventions. 1. Codificattion Making law transparent is a classical task of governments. Following the examples of Justinian and Napoleon, states enacted civil codes, criminal codes, and codes of civil and criminal procedure. The extent to which they codified law varies between common law countries, where more of the task of making law transparent is left to the courts, and civil law countries, where legislation is the primary way to make law transparent. Although common law and civil law are often presented as opposites, the amount of centralized codification is primarily a matter of degree. Both common law and civil law systems see making law transparent as a government task and do this partly through codification. However, codes have not been able to give citizens access to the information that is needed to settle their disputes. A consumer who has a dispute with a seller about the quality of the goods he bought will find in the code that he is entitled to the quality that is described in the contract, or the quality that may be expected from goods of this type in general. Parties in a divorce, or an employment contract termination, will only obtain limited information about their entitlements. Civil codes give little attention to very common causes of disputes. Transitions in long term relationships, changes of circumstances, and interactions in which both parties made a series of small, understandable mistakes, are issues that are hardly touched upon. Generally, codes are rather abstract statement of rights. They thus mainly provide a structure for reasoning, or a way to frame issues in a dispute. This can be very useful because it is easier to compare outcomes across cases if the outcomes are classified in categories of legal problems. Whilst rules from codes somewhat limit the range of possible outcomes, they rarely give much guidance for the outcome itself. The going rates for rights remain hidden for the general public. Codes hardly ever mention percentages, amounts or numbers. It is not so difficult to find the sources of government failure here, that are causes of transaction costs. Governments have limited information about the going rates of justice because they do not know how private disputes are usually settled. Codification projects tend to be the realm of academic lawyers. They have access to precedents, but, as we will see, these are also not very informative about the going rates of justice. Because the ���� � lawyers working on the code are not able to provide guidelines, they focus their attention on providing an encompassing framework for legal reasoning. Codes have the ambition to be comprehensive in this respect. This means that codification efforts are often targeted at making the code cover every imaginable problem. The discussion in codification projects is thus mostly about the different ways to systematize the law. These projects attract little or no attention from the general public, which is understandable because codes do not seem to have much impact on outcomes. Currently, the vivid academic debate about a European Common Frame of Reference for contract law is a case in point. In this academic debate, there is surprisingly little discussion about the distributive effects of the rules that are in the process of being designed (Hesselink 2006; Kerber and Grundmann 2006; Smits 2008). Another reason why codes tend to remain silent on distributive issues is related to the format of rights and obligations. Any codification of knowledge needs a model, a language and concepts in which the codification takes place (Cowan and Foray 1997). Unsurprisingly, the existing legal codifications tend to follow the model of rights and obligations. Civil codes regulate how people can establish property rights, how they can conclude a contract, under what conditions a contract is enforceable and what their obligations are to prevent damage to others (tort law). Criminal codes qualify conduct as crimes and mention the sanctions that can be attached to them. The rights and obligations model is not likely to produce concrete guidelines for settling real life disputes in which both parties interacted in a way that was less than perfect. Limited incentives are also a problem. Codification experts in the government bureaucracy are not directly responsive to client needs (Couyoumdjian 2008). Sometimes they are more concerned with the integrity and the system of their code than with the way it is used in practice. Because lawyers and repeat-playing disputants may very well have an interest in keeping legislation complex (Galanter 1974), they are unlikely to put pressure on the codification experts to do a better job Whilst plaintiffs who are one-shotters need transparency at the time they use a rule, they are unlikely to need it again in the future. So, from both sides, there is little pressure on governments to provide good information on the going rates of justice. For legislators, and as we will see for courts, an impediment to the development of objective criteria is that legal norms are thought to be binding. There are good reasons for this requirement. Legal norms often cannot be fully supported and explained by one consistent set of reasons. Law is frequently based on ‘incompletely theorized agreements’ (Sunstein 2007). Thus, the courts and the subjects applying the law cannot be left free to consider the substantive reasons behind the rule and improve it if necessary (Sherwin 2006; Schauer 2008). If legal norms are to provide law and order they must not be questioned and, therefore, they are binding. The downside of this requirement is the increase in costs of developing criteria. Widespread agreement about the norms is necessary, at least in a democracy, and they should pass through a formal legislation process. If courts are setting precedents, they have to operate cautiously. Errors in binding norms have to be avoided because they are difficult to correct at the stage of applying the norms. Thus, legislators may refrain from creating norms or set open-ended norms that give little guidance to the parties in a dispute. The political process is also ill suited for negotiating and deciding norms for distributive issues. Politicians have little to gain from taking clear stances regarding ways their citizens should divide the gains and losses of their private transactions. Only some norms – like sentencing guidelines for criminals and, currently, norms for salaries of business leaders – are interesting for politicians, because they protect the interests of many voters against the selfishness of a few. Thus, codes tend not to provide the information that people need to settle their distributive issues. This is understandable once we look at the incentives for those ���� � involved in writing the code. Once a code is enacted, however, it becomes a tool for teaching future lawyers. The code will influence their ways of thinking and doing. It reinforces the idea that the law consists of rather abstract and open ended rules that classify issues more than guiding the way towards solutions for real life problems. In the minds of lawyers working in law practice, solving actual disputes happens in an interaction between the parties and, probably, the courts. They are helped by legal expertise that operates within the broad framework of rights and obligations. Little of this expertise is codified. Lawyers are probably not unique in this respect. Cowan and Foray show that the initial high costs of codification may sustain an equilibrium in which a large group of experts has little interest in codification, although this would have high social benefits (Cowan and Foray 1997). 2. Precedents Another government intervention in the area of providing legal information that helps people to settle distributive issues is the assignment of this task to courts. Within the broad framework of rights and obligations that form the existing legal system, the courts can give guidelines about reaching outcomes in concrete disputes. This task of courts exists both in legal systems where the courts defined the framework in the past and have powers to adjust it (common law) and in legal systems where this structuring is primarily done by means of codes (civil law, Germanic legal systems). In practice, both types of legal systems have a division of labour between courts and legislators in which more abstract rules and more concrete guidelines have to be formed in an interaction process (Calabresi 1999; Ponzetto and Fernandez 2008). Building a body of case law is a slow process, however. Litigation, up to the phase of decision making by a court, takes time. Generating sufficient experience with a number of different disputes may cost five to ten years. Aligning these precedents in appellate review and through decision making by the highest courts can easily be a matter of five more years (Ponzetto and Fernandez 2008). Moreover, the prevailing culture among judges is to see a dispute as an individual problem that needs a contextualized decision. Consequently, even the highest courts may see the production of rules as a by-product of their true task: doing justice in the individual case. Thus, it can take decades before a clear guideline emerges from case law. As a result, court decisions seldom give much guidance in issues of sentencing, sharing of liability, damages, or other quantitative matters (Bovbjerg, Sloan et al. 1989). Searching databases of case law for percentages, numerical guidelines or ranges of damages leads to a very limited number of hits. Incentives are probably misaligned here as well. Judges generally do not have many reasons to create precedents that are useful for future parties (Landes and Posner 1979). They face similar problems as politicians. What they say is likely to be seen, at least by one of the groups involved, as a decision against their interests. Accordingly, making such rules will not add much to a court’s popularity. Lower courts that create clear guidelines expose themselves to criticism from higher courts. With some creativity, it is always possible to find an example of a situation in which the proposed guideline should not be applicable. Add to this the doctrine of binding precedent, or at least an obligation on the part of courts to follow an established line of precedents (Fon and Parisi 2006), and higher courts will think twice before expressing a clear guideline. It binds them for the future as well. It takes more time and effort of judges to agree on a more general guideline than on a narrow decision in one case (Sunstein 1999). Overall, courts are rather cautious. They favour rulings that are narrow, in the sense that they govern only the circumstances of the particular case, and also shallow, in the sense that they do not accept a more general theory of the legal issue (Sunstein 2008). 3. Supporting Law Faculties at Universities The market and government failures linked to the production of legal information are probably one of the reasons why states tend to invest in law faculties at universities. Within universities there is a lively debate whether legal scholars at universities should �� � � be real scientists, testing theories about law and its effects, or if they should collect, organize and publish the legal information from legislation and precedents. The latter function is certainly one that is much appreciated by law practice. Law firms and other providers of justice services buy legal information from academics in the form of law books, law review articles, and legal education. Legal academics have not always been effective in producing information about objective criteria for distributive issues. The prevailing attitude has become that academic lawyers should reflect on what happens in case law and in legislation. Therefore, they primarily follow the trends in production of norms in these sources of law. Within these categories, they are likely to focus on the information that is easiest to access and has the greatest impact. This focus tends to be case law from the highest courts and changes in codes. These changes in the law are thoroughly commented on from all sides. Academics at law faculties seldom analyze hundreds of cases from lower courts in order to find patterns in decision-making by using statistical methods. This lack of responsiveness to the needs of clients is understandable, if we look at the transaction costs of supplying this information again. It would be a time-consuming and costly business from which the results would be immediately copied by all those other academics writing their own textbooks. C. Promising Policies How can providers of justice services, courts, academics, or legislators be seduced to produce helpful objective criteria, going rates, sharing rules, prices of rights, or whatever name we give this information? This is an area that has hardly been researched yet, so we cannot do more than explore the issues. 1. Improving Incentives to Generate Guidelines A person can gain from providing information about objective criteria in many different ways. Besides financial profits, the satisfaction of helping others to solve disputes can be one such motivation. Another reason can be the fame associated with providing a lasting solution for a category of disputes. Rules sometimes carry the name of their authors. For example, the Loi Badinter that introduced strict liability for car owners causing accidents has the name of the French Minister of Justice who was the driving force behind it. The Learned Hand formula for negligence is named after the judge (and philosopher) who wrote it down in the case United States v. Carroll Towing Co (1947). If courts have to deal with many similar cases, they sometimes have an incentive to provide more clarity about the basis of their decisions. Otherwise, they will be overburdened with work, or be exposed to accusations of unequal treatment in similar cases. Other incentives work in the opposite direction. A court or decision-maker providing clear guidance for future cases will attract a lower number of cases in his future because more cases settle. This can lead to a reduction in income, as well as a loss of opportunities to make a difference (Landes and Posner 1979). More generally, the way courts are funded is an area for enquiry. It might be worthwhile to develop methods for financing courts that tie compensation to the responsibility of solving all disputes in their jurisdiction in a low cost/high quality manner within a limited amount of time. If a court’s financing would be tied to its dealing with all divorce cases or employment issues, the court is likely to look for economies of scale and for ways to increase the likelihood of settlement. Communicating guidelines for distributive issues to disputants achieves both goals. 2. Rulemaking through Intermediate Private Institutions Many schedules, guidelines, and formulas that are used within the legal system are non- binding rules. Commissions or groups of academics design schedules or formulas; judges join forces to agree about non-binding guidelines. �� � � This can hardly be a coincidence. The costs of binding distributive rules are high. They have to pass through formal procedures with limited capacity, they will be exposed to criticism from all sides, and the rules will limit flexibility of decision-makers. Thus, new, lower cost ways of rulemaking develop. As institutional economists have noted, groups may jointly form their own institutions because the transaction costs of individual coordination or coordination at the state level is too high (Brousseau and Raynaud 2006). Governments can see this as undesirable competition and, thus, try to preserve a rulemaking monopoly, but they can also choose to facilitate such private rulemaking processes. Developing nonbinding guidelines is still costly for stakeholders, and it may be difficult for them to finance these efforts. The process of rulemaking works best if groups of stakeholders are involved, but presided over by a neutral body, which governments can provide. The state can also put pressure on the private rulemaking process by threatening to use its procedures for formal and binding rulemaking if the stakeholders do not solve the issue themselves. 3. Removing Restraints on Rulemaking for Distributive Issues Another approach is to remove restraints on governments and courts that produce rules for distributive issues. A good strategy may be to have general principles as binding rules in combination with specific non-binding guidelines for recurring problems. Damages for personal injury cases, for instance, can be determined on the basis of the general and binding principle that all loss of income has to be compensated. Schedules can than give guidelines for establishing the amount of damages, whilst the parties and the courts retain the possibility to deviate from the schedule if the general principle is violated. Instead of discussing in a general way whether precedents are binding, it could be left to the courts themselves to decide how strongly they recommend that other courts follow their criteria. Similarly, a civil code could have a combination of general principles with specific criteria as guidelines for recurring issues under the article in question. The idea that codification should be comprehensive is another restriction that raises the costs of production of useful criteria. If legislators and courts would focus their efforts on criteria for the problems that are most frequent and urgent for citizens, then the costs of producing rules would drop. Depending on the costs of error and the costs of decision making, it is possible to find an optimal level of specificity of rules (Fon and Parisi 2007; Sunstein 2008). Generally, more specific rules are desirable for problems that occur frequently (Kaplow 1992). Instead of relying on interest groups, parliamentarians, individual judges, or lawyers working in the justice department to set the agenda, governments might research the most urgent needs for criteria and then focus efforts in that direction. One additional reason for adopting this strategy is that producing the right type of guidelines will diminish the costs of courts and of subsidized legal aid. 4. New Models for Sharing Rules In the information age, codification of knowledge has become much easier. The cost of codification has fallen, the ability to codify more complex phenomena has increased, and the value of codified knowledge has risen because it became less expensive to reproduce and more valuable (e.g. faster) to use (Cowan and Foray 1997). This general truth is likely to apply to legal codification as well. Objective criteria for distributive issues, the going rates of justice, have a similar role as pricing information. Sustainable business models exist for sites that inform the public about prices of goods. It is true that this is easiest for goods that are homogeneous and standardized, but sites that compare prices of rather complicated goods, including insurance or loans, have developed. They now compare products that have many relevant attributes. Similarly, it may become possible to develop bottom-up models for sharing criteria for distributive issues. Local going rates for settling recurrent issues could be uploaded to a website so that others can use them. Such a “wiki-norms solution” ���� � depends on the willingness of individuals to share their knowledge about such criteria. As of yet, it is uncertain whether it will be possible to create a forum on which the going rates of justice can be made transparent by users of the dispute system, but attempts to achieve this are under way (Barendrecht and Verdonschot 2008 and www.microjustice.org). One problem is that websites disclosing pricing information tend to be tied to spot markets where the goods in question are traded. Here, sellers have an incentive to disclose their price if it is low. Sellers or buyers usually pay a small commission to fund the infrastructure for disclosure of pricing information. Rights, however, are not traded like telephones or holiday homes. They are settled with one particular opponent, so there is little reason to inform others of offers to settle for a certain price. Other incentives have to be offered to induce people to disclose information about the going rates of justice. People could do this for money, because it enhances their reputation, or for altruistic motives. VI. Delivering the Option of a Neutral Decision A. Market Analysis The plaintiff also needs the option of a neutral decision that imposes a fair outcome on the plaintiff. This justice service is an essential element of a dispute system. It is valuable to the plaintiff, because it creates incentives on the defendant to participate and to make moves towards a fair solution for the distributive issues. Moreover, the neutral supervises the negotiation process, making aggressive bargaining tactics less likely, and can take decisions if the parties do not reach an agreement (Barendrecht 2009). Task 4. Decide Description Decision making procedure Basic technology Make option of a neutral decision available (at low cost) Best practices for dispute services/-transactions - Adjudication - Simple procedure (oral presentation, hearing, decision) - Limited fact-finding - Judicial/neutral case-management and information processing - Online formats for defining interests, distributive issues, possible solutions, decisions - Stimulate cooperative attitude - Procedural justice: voice, participation, trustworthiness, neutrality, interpersonal respect. - Discussion of possible objective criteria for outcome - Integration of decision making and settlement - Mild time pressure - Preliminary judgments in more difficult cases More generally: minimize sum of decision costs and error costs Possible providers of services - Persons with informal power - Courts - Arbitrators - Neutral fact-finders State agencies Sources of Transaction costs 1. Difficulties of concluding ex post dispute resolution agreements: - Psychological barriers - Strategic barriers 2. Insufficient incentives on neutral to provide efficient processes and fair solutions because of: - dependence on neutral - low frequency of transactions - uncertainty and complexity - monitoring difficulties. Market reactions 1. Access to neutrals on markets is unavailable or unreliable 2. States provide neutrals Table 6 Market Analysis for Services that Assist Disputants with Deciding Let us assume that a plaintiff and a defendant would look for a judge on the market for private transactions and that they found one. This is unlikely, as we have seen in Section IIIA, because parties in a dispute have difficulties to agree on a procedure, but let us ���� � imagine for a moment they have succeeded in overcoming this problem. Now how will their transaction with the private judge unfold? Normally, the client of a service provider would make clear what he wants, negotiate a price, and then monitor whether the seller will do a good job. A privately contracted judge, however, has two clients. They would need to give their judge instructions what they want from him: How to exchange views and documents? How much time for the hearing? A jury or a bench trial? How many witnesses will be called? How will they be questioned? How to conduct settlement negotiations? On many of these issues, the plaintiff and the defendant are likely to disagree, because they expect to obtain better results in one version of the procedure, or make elements of the procedure a bargaining chip if their opponent is strongly in favour of one way of dealing. Consequently, a private judge or an arbiter does not get a clear message from his clients regarding the kind of interventions they want, or the costs they want to spend. Once they find themselves before a judge, the parties are also unlikely to go to another judge because they are unhappy with the first one. The consent of the other party would be needed for this. The parties are locked into the service of this one judge, but cannot give him clear instructions. They are also unlikely to need the services of the judge in the future, because most parties will not be regular clients of courts. If, exceptionally, one of them is a regular buyer of judge services, this is bad news for the other party and likely to affect the neutrality of our private judge. Managing this neutrality is another transaction cost problem that should be solved. The private judge may be inclined to accept side payments from one of the parties to influence the decision. This is difficult to detect for the other party. In sum, the transaction costs of hiring a private judge are very substantial. The normal discipline of the market does not work well if a plaintiff tries to hire a judge. B. Current Interventions by States 1. Courts Taking into account the number and size of these transaction cost problems, it is unsurprising that governments intervened. The standard policy that developed over time was to nationalize the business of providing neutral decisions by setting up an independent judiciary. Every nation has a court system for solving civil and criminal disputes, and most countries have some form of judicial review of decisions by the administration as well. It is often possible to opt out of this government system, but we saw that this is difficult, as it requires agreement between both disputants, which is not likely to materialize (Section III.A). So most disputes are solved by formal courts set up by states, or in the shadow of their interventions. Courts face little competition. Courts set up by governments are not very efficient institutions. Clear signals of this are the amount of court delay that is pervasive around the world and the high costs of litigation (Trubek, Sarat et al. 1983; Buscaglia and Dakolias 1999; Messick 1999; Zuckerman 1999; Peysner, Seneviratne et al. 2005; George 2006; Cabrillo and Fitzpatrick 2008). This is even true for courts in developed economies that have had a stable court system for more than a century (Woolf 1996; Rhode 2004; Peysner, Seneviratne et al. 2005). Courts are slow in taking up information technology. They do not systematically incorporate innovations in conflict management in their services, although there is much criticism on the way courts intervene in disputes (Tyler 1997). The inefficiencies are so apparent, that the basic attitude of citizens is that litigation should be avoided. Governments have accepted this, which is a strange state of affairs, taking into account that courts were set up in the first place in order to help people to solve problems they cannot solve themselves. ���� � There is general agreement between scholars studying courts about the reasons for these inefficiencies. Judges have insufficient incentives to deliver high quality and low cost services (Trubek, Sarat et al. 1983; Messick 1999; López de Silanes 2002; Botero, La Porta et al. 2003; Peysner, Seneviratne et al. 2005; George 2006; Cabrillo and Fitzpatrick 2008). There is also a fair amount of consensus about the policies that are unsuitable to increase efficiency. Making money for courts available and asking judges to render neutral decisions in conflicts is not enough to create access to neutral decision making (Botero, La Porta et al. 2003). Empirical research confirms that hiring more judges does not increase the productivity of the courts (Beenstock and Haitovsky 2004), nor does a salary increase (Choi, Gulati et al. 2009). These outcomes are understandable, because just giving judges the task to decide disputes does not make it easier for clients to determine what courts should do for them, to monitor court performance, and to make them satisfy client needs. Shifting from private judges, who try to make a business from deciding conflicts, to state paid judges is not a solution for most of the transaction problems. The only real change is that judges become less dependent on the parties for their income, so they may be less tempted to take side payments from the parties, but also less inclined to do a good job for their clients. The incentives that are lacking in the market place will have to be put in place by governments. If the clients cannot decide what exactly they want from the judge, and cannot monitor her sufficiently, someone else has to take over this task. If this does not happen, a likely type of government failure that applies here is inadequate control of the bureaucracy. Individual judges may be very motivated to deliver adequate solutions for disputes in time, but their internal motivation is not complemented by external incentives (Posner 1993; Cabrillo and Fitzpatrick 2008). So let us see which incentives governments have put in place. 2. Extensive Rules of Procedure Extensive regulation of the procedure is one way to protect the interests of the clients of courts. Civil procedure rules and codes of criminal procedure, as well as their counterparts for administrative litigation, typically exist of hundreds of articles, with many details about filing claims, providing evidence, rules for hearings, options of intermediary decisions, rules for many different complications that can arise during the procedure, and rules on how the court gives reasons for its decision. This extensive regulation protects the parties to some extent because it makes the tasks of the courts more transparent and their performance thus more easy to monitor. Appeal courts, colleagues, lawyers, and legal academics can monitor whether judges follow the rules of procedure. If they do not comply, their reputation as a judge and their career opportunities will suffer. But making courts stick to the procedural rules attracts the usual risks of a rule based bureaucracy. Instead of focusing the judge on the needs of the disputants, the rules can easily become a target in themselves. In the dysfunctional variant, rules become an obsession (Bovens 2005; Bovens 2007). Moreover, rules of civil, criminal, and administrative procedure do not cover all the needs of the disputants in a systematic way. They tend to deal mostly with issues that are easy to address in general terms, like the opportunities of both parties to submit their point of view at various stages of the procedure, and formal issues like the data that documents must contain to identify the plaintiff and the defendant (see, for instance, Article 5 of the Principles of Transnational Civil Procedure: ALI and UNIDROIT 2004). More complicated, but much more essential issues like the way the parties present their case in documents, or the way a hearing is structured are mostly left to the individual lawyer of judge. The trade off between error costs and decision costs is not addressed, or only in very general ���� � terms like an obligation of the court to “resolve the dispute within a reasonable time” (Article 7 PTCP). The operation of courts is indeed rather bureaucratic, probably more bureaucratic than one can find in any other government agency. Researchers have begun to measure the efficiency of procedures by counting the number of procedural steps, the costs of accessing the procedure, or the amount of time at least one of the participants is active when compared with the duration of the procedure (see the World Bank "Doing Business" reports and Djankov, La Porta et al. 2003; Gramatikov 2008). In these terms, even simple court proceedings tend to compare unfavourably with other procedures in the bureaucracy. As a consequence of this, the expected costs of litigation can easily be higher than the value at stake (Zuckerman, Chiarloni et al. 1999). Waiting times for hearings and decisions can be months, or even many years (Messick 1999; Zuckerman 1999; Zuckerman, Chiarloni et al. 1999). Another signal of the inefficiency of court procedures is the acceptance that professional lawyers are needed to steer clients through the system. In many countries, using lawyers is even obligatory for important types of court proceedings, whereas having to hire a lawyer obviously adds to the cost of access to a neutral intervention. This is even more worrisome, because the parties can become trapped in an arms race, where they try to invest more and more in convincing the court of their position (Tullock 1980; Hirshleifer 2000; Cabrillo and Fitzpatrick 2008). It is obvious that this war of attrition is more likely to occur in situations where lawyers are paid by the hour, and thus have an interest in keeping the war going. 3. Protecting Clients and Monitoring Neutrals through Appeals Governments also help to monitor and control the courts by setting up a complaint mechanism in the form of appeal courts. A party that is not satisfied with the outcome can ask the appeal court to reverse it. Because there is always the possibility of an appeal, lower courts will know that decisions that are not truly neutral have quite a substantial probability of being detected (Shavell 2004). An obvious problem with an appeal as a solution to the monitoring problem is that it adds to the transaction costs. An appeal can be used by a powerful defendant to increase the costs of accessing justice for plaintiffs. Compared with complaint mechanisms for other services, where a customer can pick up the phone and give his feedback to a call center, appeals are extremely formal and costly. Private arbitration procedures usually do not include the possibility of appeal, which suggests that parties setting up these procedures usually think they are too costly in comparison to the advantages (Landes and Posner 1979; Barendrecht, Bolt et al. 2006). As a mechanism for enhancing the quality of outcomes, appeals have rather limited effects, because there are normally no sanctions for lower courts that are reversed in an appeal, except for those judges that have the ambition to become an appeal judge themselves. Moreover, appeal courts tend to monitor only whether the decision of the lower court is legally correct and whether the rules of procedure were observed. Many attributes of legal decisions and procedures that are important to clients are not covered by this type of monitoring. Appeal courts usually do not oversee whether courts interacted with the clients in a respectful and effective way (interpersonal justice, informational justice). They do not assess whether the decision solves the problem of the parties, whether the procedure was cost efficient, or whether the outcome was delivered timely (Cabrillo and Fitzpatrick 2008). 4. Independence of Courts Guaranteeing independence is another common element of the regulation of courts. Good salaries for judges and appointments for life are often presented as tools to prevent corruption. The measures to guarantee independence have been researched ���� � extensively. Most effective are a transparent case management system with transparent and consistent rules for the assignment of cases; predictable rewards and penalties driven by performance-based indicators, with a consequent clarification of the career paths for judicial and law enforcement officers; specific organizational roles for judicial, prosecutorial and police personnel in order to secure their own internal independence; increasing capacity to review the consistency of court rulings; and a political system in which alternation in power becomes a likely outcome of periodic elections, so that all parties have an interest in an independent judiciary that actively controls government (Buscaglia and van Dijk 2003). Unfortunately, the independence of courts is not only a valuable principle of state organization, but also a shield against incentives that would align the interests of courts closer to those of their clients (Posner 1993; Cabrillo and Fitzpatrick 2008; Choi, Gulati et al. 2009). Opportunities for interactions with the parties that are normally a good way to align the interests of principals (clients) and agents (courts) have to be curtailed because of the danger of corruption. Judges who would like to learn more about client needs may refrain from this because they want to keep a distance. Independence of courts means that courts are not fully part of the government structure with internal and external feedback mechanisms. Thus, it may not be fully appropriate to study them as entities exposed to government failure. A more adequate description of their economic position may be as service providers who have been granted a monopoly. The rules of procedure give them this monopoly position because they are the only dispute resolution forum where the defendant has to appear under the threat of a sanction in the form of an enforceable default judgment. Courts are in some respects even more problematic than other monopolists because they are more isolated from their clients. Most courts do not directly work with clients, but only through the lawyers as middlemen, who do not have a direct interest in a low cost and speedy resolution to the dispute. Monopolies usually fall under some sort of external supervision or regulation of the price and/or quality of the services they supply (Sappington 2005). This aims to guarantee that they take the interests of their client seriously enough, and in a balanced manner, when compared to their own interests. Supervision of courts is not truly independent, however. Appeal courts are part of the same hierarchy. We also saw that their supervision is limited to some aspects of the quality of outcomes and procedures, thus leaving the costs and many other quality attributes unguarded. Establishing judicial councils is the most recent attempt to improve the governance of courts (Fabri and Langbroek 2000). The major reason for their establishment has been to decrease the possibilities of the administration to influence the court system. Judicial councils can guarantee that courts are a truly independent government body by removing decisions to appoint judges and to allocate budgets from other government agents. Judicial councils can also improve the management of courts. Judicial councils, however, do not have clear responsibilities to provide low cost access to neutral interventions of appropriate quality. The rules of procedure are outside their control. Their organisations usually have no mechanisms that ensure that clients’ interests are taken into account. Because the councils are led by judges and answerable only to the community of judges, they tend to behave more like an interest group of judges than like an independent supervisor of courts. C. Promising Policies Until now, government policies have not been very successful in making high quality and low cost court interventions available to citizens. From the perspective of transaction cost analysis this is not surprising, because they have not directly tried to diminish the costs of transactions between neutral adjudicators and their clients. They focused on appeals as a monitoring device, procedural rules as a way to constrain the parties and the judge, ���� � and independence as a guarantee for neutrality. It has proven to be difficult to make courts more efficient and responsive to client needs in this way. Transaction cost analysis suggests to look elsewhere. 1. Simple, Low-Cost Default Procedures The main transaction cost problem that has to be solved is that the parties cannot determine between the two of them what is an adequate procedure for their conflict. So this has to be determined for them. Governments thus set a default procedure, from which the parties can agree to opt out. Opting out, however, is an almost theoretical option, specifically because of the strategic and psychological barriers to agreeing on a procedure, so setting the default for procedures is a very crucial decision. Default procedures (usually the ones codified in procedure rules) have traditionally been formulated by members of the legal profession. Judges, lawyers, and legal academics have an interest in providing accurate decisions. In the long run, they also have an interest in setting the defaults in a way that maximizes the total sum that disputants invest in legal dispute resolution. It is unlikely that their procedural designs will result in default rules that minimize the costs of error and the costs of decision-making (Tullock 1980; Cabrillo and Fitzpatrick 2008), which would be optimal for citizens. Governments thus have to solve this conflict of interest between the legal profession and the users of the legal system. They can design the procedures themselves or carefully supervise the way the legal profession is serving the public. If the target would be default procedures that minimize the costs of error and the costs of decision-making, then the result would probably be a simple and low cost procedure for all standard disputes, including divorce, employee dismissal, consumer problems, neighbour problems, property conflicts and business disputes. Total decision costs should probably not be more than 10 to 15% of the value at stake. If, during such a procedure, the costs of error in the particular case seem to be higher than average, a more sophisticated procedure can take off, with better fact-finding and more elaborate interaction between the parties and the court. Instead of a high cost default, with little possibilities for the parties to restrain costs, the system could provide a low cost default, with possibilities to decide on a higher level of investment in accuracy. Simplifying procedures is indeed often mentioned as an effective way to improve access to justice and court performance, both by external observers (López de Silanes 2002; Botero, La Porta et al. 2003; Islam 2003; Cabrillo and Fitzpatrick 2008; Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor 2008) and by experts in the law of procedure (Woolf 1996). This policy is likely to have other positive effects on transaction costs as well. The quality and cost-effectiveness of a simple procedure is more easy to monitor than a complex one. If the default is a low cost procedure, the defendant has more reasons to negotiate a fair solution. Bargaining failure will be less likely, because delaying tactics and threats to inflict high litigation costs on the other party will not work anymore. But is it possible to design low cost default procedures that have sufficient quality? Most disputes between individuals, as well as the conflicts that companies are involved in, are rather standard in nature. Disputes about the delivery of goods and services are mainly about how both parties contributed to quality expectations versus the actual quality of what was delivered. Disputes related to termination of long term relationships (divorce, employment, landlord-tenant, business relationships) are primarily a matter of applying objective criteria to a limited amount of standard issues, such as adequate notice periods and compensation. The scenario’s in which most crimes take place are also rather common. It is rare for the facts to be seriously disputed. If they are, the evidence is not very difficult to evaluate, and the real issue is an adequate package of retribution, treatment, restoration of harm, and possibly reconciliation. It is not being suggested that deciding disputes is easily done. In fact, some cases are very complicated. Decision making by courts, however, is not in an entirely different league as, for example, ���� � decisions about medical interventions, or decisions by senior managers. It requires expertise and skilful application of best practices. A promising approach is to have a court hearing early in the process, where a judge discusses settlement opportunities with the parties, often after giving them some guidance on the distributive issues, and also rendering summary judgments (López de Silanes 2002; Miller 2008). In this way, the courts manage their costs, and the option of a neutral intervention may become available at a much lower price. Moreover, a more active judge can compensate inequalities in skills and knowledge between the parties, and this is probably a much more effective way to create equality of arms than legal aid (Resnik 1982; Pearce 2004). Much depends, however, on the design of this preliminary hearing and the moment the hearing takes place. If extensive fact-finding is required or usual before this hearing, the costs for the parties will not be substantially reduced. The tendency to require extensive exchange of information before the court looks into the case already has a name: frontloading of costs (Peysner, Seneviratne et al. 2005). Courts should be induced to consider not only their own costs, but also the costs of the parties of initiating a procedure up to the hearing. Just a simple form may be sufficient, asking the parties to give preliminary answers to some questions about the dispute: how the relationship developed, how the problem triggering the dispute came up, the interests that have to be satisfied, which attempts to solve the problem have been made, and some possible solutions. The key documents and correspondence that have been exchanged could be added to this. Besides extensive fact-finding, the biggest impact on aggregate litigation costs probably comes from the need to use a lawyer. Thus, making this the exception, rather than the rule, is likely to help. For the most common disputes of individuals it seems to be possible to design procedures in such a way that representation is unnecessary. Experience in Japan and in many countries with small claims procedures shows that it is possible to attain high levels of efficiency and litigant satisfaction (López de Silanes 2002). Recent empirical research into the outcomes obtained by represented and unrepresented clients suggests that the so-called ‘representation premium’ is diminishing (Adler 2008). Research also shows that the more complex a procedure, the more adversarial, and the more dominated by professional lawyers, the greater the need for representation (Sandefur 2006). Thus, simplifying procedures diminishes the need for a lawyer. 2. Accountability towards Clients Other strategies may enable the clients to monitor court performance. In order to fight court delay, publication of performance data for individual judges has proven to be effective in the United States (López de Silanes 2002). Individual calendars increase accountability of individual judges and have proven to be effective tools to speed up the pace of justice (López de Silanes 2002). Likewise, the other costs suffered by users of the court services can be measured in combination with the quality of processes and outcomes as experienced by the users (Gramatikov, Barendrecht et al. 2008). Transparency of this type of data, and thus increased accountability towards clients (Cabrillo and Fitzpatrick 2008), is probably more effective than attempts to measure court performance in terms of inputs or observance of internal quality standards (Cabrillo and Fitzpatrick 2008; Albers 2009). It is also more effective than mere regulation of attributes of the procedure. Statutory time limits for decisions without ways to monitor and enforce individual performance of judges do not work (López de Silanes 2002). Specialization of courts also increases accountability. It makes courts more clearly responsible for dealing with a certain class of disputes, and creates interfaces where client needs can be made transparent. In addition, it has all the other advantages commonly associated with the division of labour (López de Silanes 2002). ���� � Another approach that seems to be successful is to make court interventions obligatory for a certain type of disputes. If courts have to be involved in order to get a divorce, to dismiss an employee, or to terminate a lease, this increases the pressure on courts to deliver decisions in time against low costs. Obviously, however, this may add to the administrative costs for the parties as well, so it is a type of policy that should only be considered for disputes that are likely to need neutral interventions anyhow. The overall approach is to create closer relationships between clients and courts, thus enabling them to monitor each other’s effectiveness and increase the incentives to use each other’s time efficiently. Part of this strategy can also be to let clients pay fees that are proportional to court effort. An example of the latter is to charge court fees based on how much of the court’s time is used (López de Silanes 2002; Cabrillo and Fitzpatrick 2008). Courts in Singapore, for example, ask increasing fees for each day of court hearings. Courts can also ask fees for the hearing and, if the case is not settled, separately for the written decision. 3. Giving Plaintiffs Choice Promising as these approaches may be, they are part of one particular strategy to solve the problem of failure on the market for neutral dispute resolution services. Instead of letting the parties decide, government decides for them by which process they will solve disputes. Are there other ways in which the market for neutral decisions can be facilitated? Having neutral ADR providers available for disputants, and waiting until the plaintiff and the defendant are ready to come, is no solution, as we saw. There should be some reason for the defendant to show up and participate in the process. One option is to make the sanction of an enforceable default judgment more broadly available. Instead of giving formal courts of law an exclusive jurisdiction, and thus a monopoly position, it may be possible to let a number of neutrals compete for plaintiffs by making their jurisdiction non-exclusive (Botero, La Porta et al. 2003). In such a setting, the plaintiff can chose the neutral with the best price/performance ratio and neutrals will start competing for business (depending on the way they are funded). Giving plaintiffs a choice can happen in many ways. Plaintiffs may have the option to address a neutral from an informal dispute system, a neutral complaint commission outside the formal court system, an ADR program offered by the defendant, a number of different courts within the formal system, courts from different states, or summary proceedings instead of full proceedings. This forum-shopping is generally seen as beneficial if it is motivated by a desire of the plaintiffs to find a low cost and high quality procedure (Ghei and Parisi 2004). However, the plaintiff will not only look at the quality and the costs of the procedure, but also at the expected outcome (Klerman 2007). If the variation in possible outcomes over the different forums is large, forum-shopping may be motivated by being able to opt for a forum that is likely to yield a more favourable outcome. Thus, neutrals may lose their neutrality as they try to attract more business from plaintiffs by rendering pro-plaintiff decisions (Landes and Posner 1979). Although there is no agreement yet about the desirability of forum-shopping, there is a consensus that it should be restrained to some extent by choice of law rules that determine which forum and substantive law regimes are accessible by the plaintiff (O'Hara and Ribstein 2000). The debate about forum- shopping is fiercest in high stakes litigation related to patents, bankruptcy, and class actions, however. This is not so surprising, because in these areas plaintiffs often have a wide range of choices available due to conflicts extending over many jurisdictions, and costs of litigation that are less relevant than the ability to influence the substantive outcome. At the opposite end of the spectrum are cases with low stakes in comparison to the costs of litigation, and low expected variability of outcomes. Most disputes of individuals are in �� � � this class, particularly if objective criteria for distributive issues have been published, so that systematic biases of courts can easily be monitored and corrected. In such an environment, plaintiff’s choice and increased competition between neutrals seems largely beneficial. Giving poor people access to multiple paths to justice makes them less dependent on particular neutrals. Moreover, defendants are quite likely to be repeat players and they can set up competing dispute resolution systems by ex ante dispute resolution clauses in their standard contracts (Klerman 2007) or by offering plaintiffs a low cost and high quality neutral alternative (see Section III). The information age, with its low cost transparency, creates new opportunities for managing the tension between letting people shop for efficient fora and for favourable outcomes. Most jurisdictions have developed rules that limit the number of possible fora (personal jurisdiction in the US, forum non conveniens in civil law countries). Thus, plaintiffs have a choice, but not a choice between an unlimited number of neutrals. Possibly, a system where the plaintiff can choose the neutral from a list can co-exist with some kind of oversight by an authority that hears appeals. This system works well in commercial arbitration. The list can give information about costs, duration, and other essential elements of the procedure (Gramatikov, Barendrecht et al. 2008). Some kind of certification of neutral adjudicators can be required. Such a system can be combined with ratings by customers on the impartiality of the neutral and other quality characteristics. This gradual opening up of the market for neutral decision making services is already happening. It is essentially what takes place if informal dispute resolution systems are incorporated in the formal legal systems (Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor 2008). This can be done in a variety of ways. First, local court-like forums can be recognized as a forum next to formal courts, so that the plaintiff has a choice. Secondly, some disputes can be left to exclusively to informal courts, and their decisions become enforceable in the formal system, either subject to full appeal at the formal courts, or under a more limited type of supervision. Our analysis suggests that giving plaintiffs a choice is preferable. Incorporation of informal systems as an exclusive forum is probably a good temporary solution, as it lowers the costs of access to a neutral decision, but in the long run it creates a new monopoly, with little incentives for the providers of the neutral service. Besides opening up the court monopoly, other tracks for innovation can be explored. For distributive issues, it may be possible to organize evaluation in such a way that the plaintiff and the defendant can obtain several independent neutral views simultaneously. This approach is an extension of the idea that a court consisting of multiple judges is less prone to judgment error or bias than a single judge. This requires, however, that disputants can inform such a forum about their interests, views, emotions and other relevant facts at low costs. At the present stage of dispute resolution technology, this is still a problem. On-line dispute resolution tools may at one time help to solve this problem. 4. Terminating Unhelpful Approaches The literature on court reform and court performance has also identified some policies that are unhelpful. Sometimes these approaches are even likely to increase the costs of transactions between clients and a neutral who helps them to decide the distributive issues. These policies generally follow from the analysis provided in the preceding paragraphs, but it is good to list them here again, as they are so frequently proposed and applied. Making legal representation obligatory or broadly subsidizing legal aid in standard litigation is an understandable policy. If court procedures are difficult to access for disputants, they need help. But in the long run, these policies weaken the incentives on courts to serve clients according to their needs. Because lawyers help clients already, courts do not need to simplify procedures. Gradually opening up the legal services �� � � market, so that those other than lawyers admitted to the bar can help clients with presenting their case, drives down costs of access to justice and will make courts more responsive to clients’ needs (Islam 2003; Baarsma, Felsö et al. 2008; Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor 2008). This should be combined with increased accountability of courts towards clients. Like any other government service, a court procedure should be understandable and accessible for citizens with average capabilities. Help should be available, but not be a necessity. Limiting competition among courts and between courts and other neutral decision makers is undesirable. So sorting out jurisdiction issues by giving one court exclusivity is not a good idea. Competition increases the possibility that services are tailored to the needs of the clients. On the other hand, specialization is helpful as well, so the optimal number of competing neutrals is higher than one but not as big as the number of lower courts in a medium sized country. Stressing quality or accuracy of decisions, without constraints on aggregate litigation costs for the disputants, is unhelpful (Cabrillo and Fitzpatrick 2008). Incentives on judges should not be distorted towards either high quality or high costs. VII. Making Arrangements Explicit and Enforcement A. Market Analysis Dispute resolution does not come to an end once a settlement is reached, or a judge has taken a decision. Settlement contracts and judgments have to make clear what the parties can expect from each other in the future. Moreover, enforcement has to be ensured. Lawyers may assist the parties in making clear what they will pay, do, or refrain from doing in the future. They do this by supplying them with contracts, which often have standard clauses that provide solutions for recurring conflicts. Unfortunately, contracting information has again a public good character, and is an experience good, so it is difficult to make money with supplying these services. Lawyers do this by individualizing the information, but their contracting services are again out of reach for many individual clients. Property rights and personal identity can also be proven by individualized documents. But it is often more efficient to register them at a central place, so this information becomes available to everyone. Setting up a registration system requires the cooperation of many people, however, so the transaction costs are high. Task 5. Stabilize Description Transparency and compliance Basic technology Supply tools to make arrangements explicit; Make costs and benefits of compliance higher than those of non-compliance Best practices for dispute services/-transactions - Standard negotiating, settlement, and decision documents (contracts/registrations) for most common disputes and issues; - Registrations, contracts, regulation (may be costly) Informal compliance mechanisms (reputation, reciprocity, identification, authority) - Expected sanctions and rewards Possible providers of services - Lawyers, mediators, notaries, other legal advisers - Community pressure - State agencies - Police - Bailiffs Sources of Transaction costs Information about contracting and making relationships transparent is public good Cooperation between many people needed to organize sufficient incentives on powerful defendants to cooperate Market reactions 1. Insufficient supply 2. Business models for delivering expertise 3. Lack of enforcement, in particular against powerful defendants Table 7 Market Analysis for Services that Assist Disputants with Stabilizing ���� � The parties must also ensure that each of them, and in particular the defendant, lives up to the agreed outcome. Enforcement of contracts, settlements, and judgments is a matter of sufficient internal motivation for the defendant, supplemented by external incentives when needed. Take the example of a consumer who is entitled to a sum in damages determined by a neutral adjudicator. The seller of the goods may be motivated to comply because he accepts this as a fair decision (Beersma and De Dreu 2003; Tyler 2006; Tyler 2006; Hollander-Blumoff and Tyler 2008), because he wants to maintain a good reputation with customers, because he sees the neutral as an authority, because other conform to the law as well (Cialdini and Goldstein 2004), or because of the threat of sanctions from the justice system (Kennett 2000). Plaintiffs have always been creative in finding ways to induce compliance. Fafchamps studied how commercial contracts are enforced in Ghana. He shows that compliance with contractual obligations is mostly motivated by the desire to preserve personalized relationships based on mutual trust. Harassment is the main form of debt collection. Other enforcement mechanisms – court action, reputation effects, use of illegitimate force – are less important. Contract renegotiation is common, suggesting that compliance to outcomes is often bought by additional concessions (Fafchamps and Lund 2003; Fafchamps 2004). The formation of groups that reserve important relationships to group members also helps to enhance enforcement. These groups include trade organizations for commercial contracts. Clans, local communities and extended families may take care of compliance with land use agreements, employment contracts, and family relationships (Ouchi 1980; Greif 2006). Property rights on land are often collectively held so that the group can jointly protect the property against threats from outsiders (Deininger 2003; Fitzpatrick 2005). However, these ways of organizing compliance have high costs and only work in a limited number of situations. Self-enforcing contracts can help if reputation for either one of the parties is important enough to perform, or if the value of the transaction is low (MacLeod 2007). Strong groups also have their drawbacks. The number of transactions with people other than group members will be more limited. People from within the community cannot easily sell their property to outsiders or trade with them in other ways. Employment relationships or marriages with outsiders are more difficult if compliance is organized in this way. Because the group is ‘closed,’ the likelihood of conflict with outsiders who want access to its resources is substantial. Inside the group, the members organize their own enforcement, and it may be that individuals are severely punished for minor offences, or that there is an internal hierarchy in which some people (men, people with resources such as political connections) do markedly better than others (women, poorer persons) (Goldstein and Udry 2008). If we look at the most common categories of disputes again, it is clear that these private enforcement mechanisms will often not help. Quality of goods or services will mostly be a problem if the parties expect little future interaction and if the trade has a high value. Conflicts in long term relationships are often related to termination and end in settlements where one party has to pay a sum of money as compensation, together with some obligations for both parties regulating their future (lower level) interactions. The members of the group may not have sufficient reason to help the plaintiff to enforce these outcomes against another member of the same community. In case of tort claims, or human rights violations, where compensation or some sort of sanction is likely to be part of the outcome of the dispute resolution process, next to obligations to refrain from similar acts in the future, the group may have insufficient means to influence an outside perpetrator. ���� � From the perspective of the plaintiff, organizing compliance can thus be a difficult task. Many different people may have to be involved in order to gain sufficient influence over the defendant. B. Current Interventions by States Making relationships transparent through contracts and property rights, as well as enforcement of these rights, is often seen as one of the core tasks a government in a free market economy should perform. As we may expect by now, governments are not necessarily very effective in overcoming these transaction cost problems. They have found it difficult to set up registrations, provide contracting formats, and organize enforcement. In many countries, these government services still do not reach a substantial proportion of the population. Taking a closer look at the way these policies influcence transaction costs may help to understand why. 1. Registrations of Identity One way the government can help to make relationships transparent and reduce the costs of enforcement is by the registration of rights. This begins with giving people a means to prove their identity so that they can be recognized as owners of property, parties to a contract, or beneficiaries of social security (Setel, Macfarlane et al. 2007; Szreter 2007; Barendrecht and Van Nispen 2008; Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor 2008; Sabates-Wheeler, Devereux et al. 2009). Informal ways of ascertaining identity have emerged in many communities. Szreter describes how Anglican churches set up parish registers in rural 17th century England, and thus satisfied a local need to establish age, lines of inheritance, legitimization of bastardy, and eligibility for primitive forms of social security. Obtaining this registration was an important reason to be a member of the church, so the church was eager to supply this service. Once migration to the cities started in the 19th century, the local parish registers could not keep up with the demand for registration and the state took over (Szreter 2007). Building an effective registration system is difficult and costly. A birth registration system requires an initial investment through some form of information technology. Then, it is necessary that parents have sufficient incentives to go through the registration procedure, and bureaucrats have sufficient reasons to help them. Network effects add to the transaction costs. If many people refrain from registering because they face high costs of queueing or travelling, the system becomes unreliable. Entering the system often has high costs because parents have no valid documents themselves, and must first start formal court procedures to obtain these. They may also fear becoming subject to taxation. Civil servants may have insufficient incentives to help the poorest of the poor to register. For them, the transactions that are necessary to make registration happen are less likely to occur (Setel, Macfarlane et al. 2007; Barendrecht and Van Nispen 2008). 2. Registrations of Property Rights Registrations of property rights in land (titling) make clear which persons have which rights to use, sell, or appropriate which pieces of land. Informal ways of making entitlements to land transparent develop locally, because communities profit from this once their land has a certain threshold value (Rakodi and Leduka 2004). At later stages of development, this is typically a task that is taken over by governments. More security and transparency in entitlements to land has been shown to lead to a higher investment of urban squatters in their homes (Field 2005), better access to the labour market (Field 2007), better health conditions, and other social benefits (Payne, Durand-Lasserve et al. 2007). Security of interests in rural land is also linked to higher investment and productivity (Goldstein and Udry 2008; Fenske 2009; Galiani and Schargrodsky 2009). The role of titling in this, however, is contested (Deininger 2003; Cousins, Cousins et al. 2005; Payne, Durand-Lasserve et al. 2007; Otto 2009). The link ���� � between having a formal title and increased access to credit (with land as a collateral) seems to be weak (Payne, Durand-Lasserve et al. 2007). Property rights protection through registration (titling) is difficult to achieve. Boundaries have to be surveyed, documents must be drafted, and registration has to be undertaken by a trustworthy neutral. If conflicting claims of property arise, they have to be decided on by a neutral or another third party. Tenure rights are often ambiguous, or in the hands of poorly delineated families or communities, so there is a lot of sorting out to be done before a piece of land can be registered in one person’s name. This registration almost certainly has some distributive effects (Knight 1992; Payne, Durand-Lasserve et al. 2007). Thus, it becomes attractive to use the system to one’s advantage, which the affluent may do better than the poor, and men better than women. Besides being tools of the powerful, registrations can quickly become outdated, as use patterns change and not every person involved has incentives to register his rights on land. Finally, having a formal title means little if there is no protection against eviction by the more powerful. In summary, titling systems require many transactions between many people that must all work well. The network effects are such that using the system becomes more valuable if more people participate. This is unlikely to occur in rural settings (Cousins, Cousins et al. 2005; Otto 2009) and not always likely in urban settings (Lanjouw and Levy 2002). 3. Default Rules for Contractual Relationships Governments also play an important role in making explicit what the parties in a relationship can expect from each other in the future. The market is very active here, as lawyers supply boiler plate clauses that people can use in their contracts. But they do so against the background of default rules for contracts that are government made. If the parties have not regulated their future relationship in an explicit contract, it will be assumed that they have made the same arrangement as others in a similar situation (a majoritarian default rule, see Ayres and Gertner 1989; Korobkin 1998). Civil codes and case law determine these default rules. Because of the way the information market operates, it is questionable whether sufficient contracting expertise reaches the citizens who need it. Lawyers and other legal information providers are probably hesitant to share this information widely. Governments may also have insufficient incentives to produce suitable default arrangements for – say – the consequences of divorce, settlement of property disputes in a village, or an employment relationship that is likely to be adjusted many times during a 10 year period. In this respect, default rules are similar to objective criteria. Legislators and courts will not profit much from them, and have to spend a lot of effort on formulating them (see Section VB). Another problem is that drafting default rules is usually left to lawyers. They may be rather task-oriented, and use a rights and obligations approach to the relationship that does not take into account the emotional and relational issues that also determine whether a relationship will be successful. . A final transaction cost problem mentioned in the contracting literature is that default rules are sticky. Both parties have to agree to deviate from them, and this raises the costs of contracting for the parties to relationships for which the default rule is not appropriate (Korobkin 1998; Ben-Shahar and Pottow 2006). 4. Enforcement by State Because there are situations in which market mechanisms clearly fail to produce enforcement, a demand for public enforcement arose (Polinsky and Shavell 2000). State enforcement typically builds on the authority of courts and uses the threat of sanctions. There is ample evidence that this type of enforcement can work and is necessary, ���� � particularly for arms length commercial transactions such as providing credit (Jappelli, Pagano et al. 2005). Countries differ in how they organize public enforcement of dispute outcomes: some leave it to the courts, some organize a regulated private profession to deal with it, a few put the executive in charge, and others have a system of mixed responsibility (Henderson, Shah et al. 2004). Public enforcement of court decisions is problematic in most countries, however (Kennett 2000). It consists of a process of finding assets of the debtor, bringing them under control of the creditor, letting them be sold publicly, and bringing the proceeds in the hands of the creditor. Debtors who frustrate this process may have to be threatened with sanctions and put in jail (Henderson, Shah et al. 2004). This requires an intricate cooperation between plaintiffs seeking enforcement, bailiffs, police, banks, and bankruptcy lawyers to sell the property of a debtor and allocate the proceeds. Besides these network problems, government failures that are likely to be present are absence of information (about the assets of the debtor), and insufficient incentives to perform the tedious and sometimes dangerous task of making people pay what is due to others. Henderson et al. report five categories of problems as the most important obstacles to enforcement: the efficiency and integrity of the judicial enforcement and justice system, delays, costs, inadequate access to information, and lack of accountability of the actors in the enforcement process (Henderson, Shah et al. 2004). C. Promising Policies What can governments or NGOs do to lower the transaction costs of making expectations in relationships explicit and ensure that these solutions to a dispute are enforced? This is a far-reaching question, and the answers are strongly related to the core functions of contract law, property law, and registration of rights. These functions are extensively debated in economics, law, development studies, and other disciplines that theorize about the ordering of relationships. We cannot do more than indicate the type of reasoning that is suggested by the transaction costs approach and link it to some of the research that has recently become available. 1. Formalization As Is and Step by Step Identity registrations and registrations of property rights are valuable tools for making relationships explicit and transparent so that people can rely on each other. In the process of registration, however, rights are allocated. People who are registered as citizens get access to pensions, schools, and other government services. Registering property means a piece of land will now be owned by a man, a community, and (less frequently) a woman or a farmer. Because of these distributive effects, the dynamics of disputes may arise (Payne, Durand-Lasserve et al. 2007). The registration system needs to have a mechanism to resolve these disputes fairly, making it more costly to operate, and less accessible. The emerging consensus is to lower these transaction costs by gradual formalization. Formalization processes should increase security of tenure instead of allocating property rights. Giving people an address on a street, and providing infrastructure (roads, sewerage, water) creates increased trust that their position will be recognized. It already helps if personal use of land is registered, and this can later be upgraded to long-term leases or freehold (Durand-Lasserve and Selod 2007). If different people from a family or a group use the land or have other claims on it, registering these claims at least protects the groups against outsiders. Registration of transactions and outcomes of disputes about land is generally less costly than registering rights because it focuses on situations where the clients felt a direct need for transparency, thus it is more demand-driven. These non-formal ways of increasing tenure security focus on registering the situation as it is and as the need arises. Registering is seen more as making existing relationships ���� � transparent than making them legal. Transparency can be achieved by noting which use has been made of land by which persons, for how long, and by which agreement with whom. Such a more open system does not try to resolve all issues that may arise, but may do enough to make the relationships workable for the foreseeable future (Payne, Durand-Lasserve et al. 2007). If new disputes arise, they can be resolved more easily on the basis of this information. The outcomes of the disputes can be made transparent in the system, and thus the registration will gradually reflect more of the legal status of the land. The gradual approach fits in the paradigm of minimizing error costs and decisions costs. Economies of scale can be reached in large scale titling programs, and it is important to look for them, but taking just one big leap to registration of individual property rights for every piece of land has high decision costs. It can also lead to unfair outcomes and, thus, high costs of error. A similar step by step approach may work for identity documents. Uncertainties in birth dates, misspelling of names, or even uncertainties about parentage can be seen as an obstacle to registration. If these issues can be resolved quickly, the increased certainty is valuable. But in many countries, these issues require more extensive and costly procedures on higher levels of administration, or even higher courts (Barendrecht and Van Nispen 2008). Besides making procedures less formal, and thus reducing the decision costs (see Section VI.C), one option is simply to live with the uncertainties for the time being. A person is better off with identity documents showing that he was born either on 24 March 1980 or 24 March 1982 compared to not being able to prove his identity at all. Sorting out his birth date can probably wait until he is close to the age where he is entitled to a pension. Access to registration is in many ways similar to access to the neutrals who have to settle a dispute. Clients can become dependent on the registrar in similar ways. A viable strategy is to make the civil servants in charge of registration more responsive to client needs. It helps if clients have multiple points of access, so that they can avoid civil servants who have backlogs or ask for bribes. This is available in the e-seva projects in Andhra Pradesh, India, where citizens can use kiosks in different sites to interact with the government about permits and registrations (Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor 2008). 2. Menus for Making Relationships Explicit The market for contracts, settlement agreements, and written judgments is again a market for expertise. Unfortunately, the recurring public good problem and experience good problem make it difficult to get the right expertise to clients. Standard documents that make the relationship explicit are difficult to obtain. These documents would lay down the expectations that parties could realistically have about their future relationship in case of a divorce, a neighbour dispute, or a termination of employment. Some kind of ex ante formalization of long term relationships can also be beneficial, as in a marriage contract, a will, or a contract about cooperation between business partners. Here, there seems to be ample room for innovation. Instead of one set of default rules provided by the state, the parties can be offered a menu of choices for suitable contractual arrangements (Ayres 2006). Production and publication of fair and efficient arrangements by private parties can be stimulated (Hadfield and Talley 2006). Governments, or private parties, could also begin to certify certain standard arrangements as fair and valid. Instead of regulating agreements by limiting freedom of choice ex post through courts that invalidate a contract, governments could stimulate productive and fair relationships ex ante. The way relationships are regulated can be enriched with knowledge of the social sciences. The legal way of making expectations explicit is to write down rights and ���� � obligations. Relationships, however, are more than tasks and duties. It also helps if people know about each others’ interests, wishes and fears. Besides commercial interests, relational and process interests can have a place in a contract. Besides sanctions and bonuses, it can be useful to talk about situations in which both parties consider the relationship to be a success or a failure. Besides an allocation of risks, it is useful that the parties think about the main threats to the relationship, and determine ways to share gains and losses if these materialize (see Section V about objective criteria). In contracting practice, there is some activity aimed at reinventing relational contracting in this direction. In complex infrastructure projects, contract charters can form the basis for the cooperation between the parties (Walker and Hampson 2003; Van den Berg and Kamminga 2006). In these charters, the parties lay down how they see the relationship and how they will communicate. Another way in which governments can facilitate the market for stabilizing relationships is by ensuring that contracts can easily be used across jurisdictions so that economies of scale can reached. The basic tensions and interests caused by an employment relationship are similar in Korea, the Netherlands, and Zimbabwe. Cultural differences will certainly exist, and these can be reflected in different templates from which the parties can choose. Contract law, however, departs from freedom of contract everywhere, and governments can take care that contracting parties are not surprised by unexpected forms of illegality. The least governments could do is to list the situations in which their courts will not enforce a clause in the types of contract that are most essential for the economy. This sort of regulation would save parties involved in such a contract from having to ask for specialized legal advice. 3. Facilitating Compliance Mechanisms The transaction costs of organizing compliance can be reduced by making it easier to exchange information about compliance. People tend to improve enforcement by investing in connectedness: if they share more information with more people about performance of a debtor, they have more impact on his reputation (Dhillon, Rigolini et al. 2006). This connectedness can probably be facilitated by offering internet-platforms on which information about compliance can be shared. EBay enables buyers to exchange information about sellers. Hotels and restaurants are now routinely evaluated by customers on the internet. Internet networking sites such as Facebook and LinkedIn make it possible to share information about people in new ways as well. Likewise, the status of compliance with settlements or judgments can be reported. This might start with a neutral mention of an issue as unresolved. In case of continued non-performance, the information could go more towards the direction of shaming. It would certainly be necessary to protect debtors against people abusing such tools, but this protection is also needed for the existing enforcement mechanisms. Other strategies to increase access to compliance can be developed. The literature on enforcement suggests simplifying procedures for enforcement and privatizing enforcement tasks whilst putting them under neutral supervision, and organizing access to information about the whereabouts of assets of the debtor (Henderson, Shah et al. 2004). 4. What Works When facilitating the market for obtaining enforcement, governments and NGOs should keep in mind that the basic technology of providing compliance is not only a matter of incentives. The joint effects of intrinsic motivation and of external triggers living up to the decision are what matters. There are many reasons why people might comply with what they have agreed on as a dispute solution or with a judgment by a neutral. They may consider this to be their duty, feel it is fair to do so, or be afraid of sanctions. The psychological literature on compliance suggests several mechanisms to induce ���� � compliance: reciprocation, the human tendency to be consistent in their acts, imitation of what others do, positive reinforcement, identification, and authority (Cialdini and Goldstein 2004). A culture where disputes are considered to be normal, where solutions are found in cooperation between the parties and a neutral, and where compliance is expected can help at least as much as the threat of formal sanctions. These approaches have clear links to the attempts in many countries to decrease recidivism. In the ‘What Works’ literature, the internal motivation of perpetrators to participate in programs is seen as a crucial factor (MacKenzie 2006; Wormith, Althouse et al. 2007). In many other ways, these programs are combining classical enforcement (monitoring, increasing the probability of sanctions) with positive incentives and factors that are known to enhance internal motivation (structure, respectful treatment, conditional help with obtaining housing and work). Expertise regarding law enforcement in order to reduce crime is far more developed compared to the know-how on enforcement of property rights and contracts. The similarity between both types of enforcement is their attempt to induce people to have more respect for the legitimate interests of others. VIII. Complementarities A. Market Analysis Talking about a system suggests something more than the sum of its parts. That is certainly true for dispute systems (Bendersky 2003). Each of the five justice services we discussed is more valuable if the other services are supplied as well (Barendrecht 2009). Stimulating the defendant to enter a cooperative dispute resolution process (Task 1) is a more valuable service if there is adequate help with negotiation (2), information about norms for distributing value (3), and the option of a low cost neutral decision (4), which can be enforced (5). A plaintiff gets more value from negotiation assistance (Task 2), if he has the option of asking for a low cost neutral decision (4) that is enforceable (5). Norms for distributive issues (Task 3) make adjudication (4) easier and the ideas about fairness incorporated in these norms make it more likely the outcome can be enforced (5). A good basic structure for making an agreement explicit such as a standard contract (Task 5), can also be used to identify issues for negotiation (2), and serve as a template for a judgment (4). These complementarities, or connectedness between services, are a cause of transaction costs. Before suppliers can offer effective services, they have to ensure that the other services are available as well. This network has to be established and adjusted if an innovation takes place in one of the tasks. If mediation services provide better negotiation assistance, this creates new opportunities for adjudication as well. Providers of legal services understand this and try to offer integrated services. Lawyers help plaintiffs to contact defendants, coach them in negotiations, inform them about distributive issues, and litigate for them. Judges decide cases, but nowadays also help clients to settle distributive issues, and sometimes even to problemsolve in integrative negotiations. This coordination may be difficult, however. Judges do not interact frequently with lawyers, because they want to keep a distance out of worries to lose their independence. At the interfaces between negotiation, bargaining, and adjudication there is also competition between lawyers and judges. Judges tend to promote a more active and problemsolving attitude of courts, whereas lawyers like courts to stay passive and only become active if one of the lawyers asks them to intervene. ���� � B. Current Interventions by States 1. Legal System Reform: Law and Development Governments have invested in making dispute services work in concert. Many programs aimed at enhancing the rule of law in developing countries have organized efforts at various levels of the system. Codification projects providing information about norms were combined with investments in improving the court system, and sometimes also with setting up an independent legal profession that can help to negotiate disputes (Jensen 2002; Carothers 2006; Dam 2006). The gist of the papers assessing these policies is a negative evaluation of their effects (Davis and Trebilcock 2008; Tamanaha 2009). This lack of success should hardly be a surprise, if we use the perspective of the transaction costs on the markets for justice. These policies tend to combine approaches that were not very effective in making dispute transactions happen in the first place. Moreover, they did not address some important elements of the dispute supply chain: having people meet, helping them to negotiate, organizing low cost access to neutrals, and guaranteeing enforcement. 2. Reforms in Developed Economies In developed economies, policies that aim to reinforce all five necessary and sufficient elements of a dispute system are unheard of. Civil procedure reform (Zuckerman, Chiarloni et al. 1999) focuses on the rules of procedure; court reform on the organization of courts; mediation programs on letting judges send people to mediation (Wissler 2004); codification efforts on writing down rights and obligations; tort reform on changing rules of tort law (Currie and MacLeod 2008); consumer protection law on improving the substantive rights of consumers; reforms of the legal profession on increasing competition among legal service providers. All tend to be separate issues. They are dealt with at different times by different commissions and with different constituencies. Improvements in one section of the justice system is unlikely to have effect, though, if other parts of the system are not taken into account as well. Referring disputants to mediation is not very effective if it happens just before the court decides, and most of the costs of litigation haven been made. Improving the organization of courts is unlikely to be beneficial for clients, unless the procedures by which courts adjudicate are also reconsidered. Changing substantive rules of tort law without looking at the incentives on lawyers and courts makes little sense. C. Promising Policies While the connectedness between various types of dispute resolution services is a problem, it is also an opportunity. If the weakest links in the supply chain can be found and addressed, the other services will become more accessible and profitable to supply as well. 1. Supply Chain Approach to Access Strong complementarities suggest an integrated, supply chain approach to justice services. Governments could focus on the services with the biggest complementarities, hoping that improvements in one part of the dispute resolution market will spill over to adjacent markets. Low cost access to neutrals, for instance, is an efficient way to improve the negotiation climate in the shadow of the law and to drive down the aggregate costs of dispute resolution. This is especially true if judges or other neutrals approach the problem in the same way as the clients do in their negotiations. If legal rules and procedures used by the court focus on interests and link to the formats of (integrative and distributive) negotiations, the supply chain will run more smoothly. Low costs of access are more affordable and, thus, can be paid by the parties who use the services themselves in the �� � � form of court fees, which is also a way to make neutrals answerable to their clients more directly. Such a policy may be hard to implement, though, because it requires rethinking the relationship between courts, their clients, and their sponsors within government. Another policy with positive spillovers is the publishing of the going rates of justice for the most important disputes through guidelines or otherwise. As we saw, this not only makes bargaining failure less likely, it also enables clients to monitor the lawyers that help them and the neutrals who decide their distributive issues. Because expectations of all players involved will be more aligned if objective criteria are widely shared, the overall costs of disputing will drop. Thus, justice transactions become more attractive to conclude, and more accessible for clients. This policy is a modern way to fulfil an old ideal: codification. A final example of choosing a policy with strong complementarities is to invest in default formats for common relationships. Marriage contracts, employment agreements, and business partnerships can be made explicit in standard ways, with menus for different arrangements that deal with the typical sources of tension and conflict. These formats can bring the benefits of explicit contracting within reach of every citizen. Such standard documents can also take over the functions of contractual default rules, serve as a template for dispute resolution, and facilitate the writing of judgments by courts. 2. Monitoring, Accountability and System Ownership Because of the strong complementarities between the different justice services, it also makes sense to monitor the performance of the system. Current monitoring systems and measurement efforts tend to focus on the performance of courts (Cabrillo and Fitzpatrick 2008; Albers 2009). System wide performance measurement would also gauge the abilities of the system to facilitate settlement negotiations and to organize enforceable outcomes. Besides the performance of courts as decision makers, the availability of clear substantive rules (objective criteria) and the enforceability of outcomes would be assessed. Such a method could measure the time and cost for the average user to go through the process, from the first attempt to obtain outside help to get in contact with the other party, up to the final outcome (Gramatikov, Barendrecht et al. 2008). The quality of the procedure and the quality of the outcome can be measured against several criteria (Gramatikov, Barendrecht et al. 2008), preferably from the perspective of the user (Masser 2009). A monitoring system could also try to visualize the number and the complexity of the steps an individual has to take in order to obtain an outcome, as demonstrated by the work of De Soto and several others (De Soto 2000; Djankov, La Porta et al. 2003; Masser 2009 and the yearly Doing Business reviews by the World Bank). Supply chain monitoring makes transparent what can be expected from suppliers in the system. If employment disputes are costly to deal with and lead to low quality outcomes, governments can revise their policies in this area. Courts, legal services providers, and possible new entrants in the relevant justice market will adjust their services in response to this information as well. Clients can make more informed decisions about using the system, and press for change if necessary. 3. Focus on Problem Categories Making a justice system work across the board is a daunting task for civil servants at ministries of justice and for managers within the judiciary. They often feel responsible for dealing with every thinkable dispute and crime. If they see their task in this way, they are likely to issue comprehensive codes and procedural rules that are general in character. Courts tend not to be very specialized, and deal with a broad variety of disputes. Performance of such a broad system is difficult to measure, because the same procedure is applied to a great variety of disputes with different issues, different needs for fact-finding and different client budgets. �� � � Focusing on problem categories, as well as improving the supply chain for these categories, seems to be a more successful approach. Law firms tend to specialize, and court specialization is believed to lead to higher efficiency (Cabrillo and Fitzpatrick 2008). The complementarities in a dispute system point in the same direction. It makes more sense to systematically improve access to justice for situations such as divorce, employment disputes, and business conflicts, as opposed to trying to reform courts, to invest years in overall codification, or to subsidize legal aid in general. IX. Conclusions Our analysis took the perspective of justice as a set of goods that are delivered by people to other people. This market for justice does not work perfectly, and that is where governments intervene with justice policies. The analysis from the perspective of transaction costs suggests that many justice policies are less than a perfect fit to the problems they need to address. Table 8 summarizes the results. If two opponents find it difficult to choose a procedure, it does not help to offer them mediation, send them each to a lawyer, or make sophisticated but expensive litigation available. Stimulating cooperative dispute resolution by social norms, facilitating the market for neutral dispute services, and requiring repeat-players to offer an accessible dispute system is likely to be more effective. Access to simple, low-cost default procedures is needed to induce fair settlements. Giving plaintiffs a choice between different procedures and neutrals – without consent of the defendant being necessary – can help to achieve this. Accountability of courts (and other neutrals) to clients is also important. Existing checks and balances on courts, such as extensive rules of procedure and appeals, have important disadvantages. Focusing on rules of procedure easily lead to bureaucracy and makes procedures less transparent for disputants. Appeals tend to improve the formal, legal quality of outcomes. But they do not stimulate judges to diminish the costs of litigation, to provide procedural justice, and create outcomes for disputes that fit the needs of the parties. Moreover, these mechanisms do not influence the quality of settlements, which are the primary way to resolve disputes. Where the public good character of information is the problem, governments can create additional incentives to supply the needed information. Without such incentives, it is highly unlikely that negotiation expertise, codes, precedents, or law review articles will ever meet the information needs of those clients that cannot afford to hire a lawyer. Governments and NGOs can make information more accessible by providing public legal education programs or needs-based codification, by stimulating production of guidelines for settling distributive issues, or by developing open source models for sharing information about objective criteria. Structuring settlement negotiations, menus for contractual relationships, and certification of fair standard contracts are also helpful ways to enhance access to justice. The complementarities between justice services suggest an integrated approach, aimed at the entire supply chain for each type of disputes. Monitoring, accountability and system ownership are highly important here. Mediation programs, codification projects, reform of civil procedure, or projects aimed at improving access to courts are less likely to be effective than measures that target all elements of dispute systems for categories such as property disputes, employment issues, or business conflicts. Making powerful defendants participate and creating transparency of property rights, and their enforcement, are best seen as gradual processes, in which many people contribute to a portfolio of incentives on the defendant to cooperate. ���� � Tasks Basic technology Sources of Transaction Costs Existing Policies Additional sources of transaction costs Possible innovative policies/services that lower transaction costs 1. Meet Make costs and benefits of participation for defendant higher than costs and benefits of fighting, or avoiding Difficulties of selling cooperative dispute services to opponents: - Psychological barriers - Strategic barriers Cooperation between many to make powerful defendants cooperate 1. Prohibition of violence and enforcement of this prohibition 2. Judgment by default 3. Stimulating mediation 1. Costs of monitoring and enforcement prohibition violence 2. Costs of organizing credible threat of default judgment 1. Stimulating cooperative dispute resolution by social and legal norms 2. Opening markets for neutral dispute resolution services 3. Regulating ex ante dispute resolution agreements 4. Requiring repeat-players to offer an accessible dispute system 5. Co-opting powerful defendants gradually 2.Talk Support integrative negotiation (interest based) Information about negotiation and conflict management is public good and experience good 1. Framing disputes in terms of rights and obligations 2. Legal aid 3. Mediation aid 1. Polarization in relationship governance 2. Increased need for legal advice 3. Search, bargaining, coordination and monitoring costs client-lawyer relationship 4. Increased costs of hiring neutral 5. Unilateral legal services create extra demand at other side (externalities) 1. Education in negotiation and conflict management 2. Economies of scale in communication and negotiation advice 3. Structuring settlement negotiations 3. Share Supply information about fair shares (sharing rules, objective criteria) Information about fair solutions (objective criteria, going rates of justice) is public good and experience good 1. Codification 2. Precedents 3. Legal academics 1. Governments lack information about client needs and going rates of justice 2. Insufficient incentives to produce and publish useful legal information 3. Limitations imposed by political process 1. Improve incentives to make guidelines 2. Privatize production of objective criteria 3. Non-binding rules and precedents 4. Needs based codification (instead of comprehensive codification) 5. Sharing rules (open source) 4. Decide Make option of a neutral decision available (at low cost) Difficulties of concluding ex post dispute resolution agreements Insufficient incentives on neutral to provide fair/low cost processes 1. Setting up courts 2. Extensive rules of procedure 3. Protecting clients through appeals 4. Independent courts 1. Bureaucratic procedures 2. Appeals increase costs of access 3. Appeals distort incentives to improve quality and diminish costs of procedure 4. Independence is shield against incentives 1. Simple, low cost default procedures 2. Accountability towards clients 3. Giving plaintiffs choice (competition between neutrals) 4. Terminating unhelpful policies (obligatory legal representation, etc.) 5. Stabilize Supply tools to make arrangements explicit; Make costs and benefits of compliance higher than those of non- compliance Information about contracting and making relationships transparent is public good Enforcement requires transactions with many participants 1. Registrations of identity 2. Registrations of property rights 3. Default rules contracts 4. State enforcement 1. Distributive effects of allocating rights to individuals 2. Information is public good 3. Insufficient incentives from government 4. Costs of imposing sanctions 5. Coordination and monitoring costs 1. Gradual formalization as is, with access to dispute resolution 2. Menus for making expectations in relationships explicit 3. Certification of fair standard contracts 4. Facilitating reputation mechanisms that enhance compliance Supply Chain Approach Strengthen links between tasks Complementarities (connectedness) 1. Legal system reform 1. Insufficient incentives from government 1. Supply chain approach to access 2. Integrated dispute resolution services 3. System monitoring and ownership 4. Focus on problem categories Table 8 : Sources of Transaction Costs on Markets for Justice and Policies that may Reduce them. ���� � In some ways, governments may do too much. A court decision on all issues is usually available, although it may be sufficient that courts facilitate settlement and decide on the remaining distributive issues. Governments also tend to have a monopolistic attitude towards production of law, supply of neutrals, and enforcement of law. This may crowd out market activities in these areas. Governments tend to regulate legal services in ways that are not clearly linked to the goal of resolving disputes in a fair and efficient manner, and their regulation efforts seem poorly related to the causes of market failure and government failure. Analysis of the market for justice services also sheds new light on the viability of business models for providers of legal services. The success of the one-lawyer-one-client model is probably not so much a conspiracy of the legal profession (Hadfield 2000), but can instead be explained by the tendency of disputants to look for a trusted adviser in combination with the public good and experience good character of information. This model is reinforced by the prevailing framework of rights and obligations as tools to solve disputes. The one-lawyer-one-client model is not viable, however, for serving justice needs of the poor. This adversarial model is also less attractive in the light of modern conflict resolution and negotiation technology. Mediation fits these developments, but it is not viable as a business model because of the difficulties disputants face when they have to agree on a dispute process ex-post. Finally, the transaction costs approach of this paper offers a new explanation why attempts to implement the rule of law top down have largely failed. Writing legislation, setting up courts, organizing the procecution, and regulating the legal profession is unlikely to create access to justice. Such justice policies have no answer to the basic transaction costs problems that plague the market for justice. Affordable and sustainable justice services will emerge bottom up, because people have justice needs. Governments should facilitate this, by lowering the costs of agreeing to a dispute procedure, by stimulating the dissemination of information that fits the needs of clients, and by lowering the costs of organizing enforcement. The analysis thus suggests that smarter justice policies are possible. The basic technologies for supplying justice are available. If the transaction costs can be lowered, these technologies can lead to innovation on the market for justice services (Islam 2003; Hadfield 2008). Legal entrepreneurs, courts, and NGO’s may step in to develop low cost approaches that fit the basic technologies and the best new practices. Examples are development of neutral “meet and talk services”, internet portals for objective criteria/going rates of justice, low cost/high quality default procedures, procedural rules that provide choice of neutrals for plaintiffs, formats for making expectations explicit in common relationships, and reputation mechanisms for enforcement. Governments should stimulate these innovation processes. They, and the NGO’s working in the justice sector, can develop smart institutions that facilitate justice markets in a way that minimizes transaction costs. The state can be guardian of the rule of law by letting justice grow, on the micro- level, from the relationships between clients and justice providers. ���� � Literature Adler, M. (2008). The Potential and Limits of Self-Representation at Tribunals: Full Research Report End of Award Report. Swindon, ESRC Albers, P. (2009). "The Asssesment of Court Quality: Hype or Global Trend?" Hague Journal on the Rule of Law 1(01): 53-60. ALI and UNIDROIT (2004). The Principles of Transnational Civil Procedure. Allred, K. G. (2005). Relationship Dynamics in Disputes: Replacing Contention with Cooperation. Handbook of Dispute Resolution. M. L. Moffitt and R. C. Bordone. New York, Jossey-Bass: 83-98. American Bar Association (1994). Comprehensive Legal Needs Study. Chicago, American Bar Association. Ayres, I. (2006). "Menus Matter." The University of Chicago Law Review: 3-15. Ayres, I. and R. Gertner (1989). "Filling gaps in incomplete contracts: an economic theory of default rules." Yale Law Journal: 87-130. Baarsma, B., F. A. Felsö, et al. (2008). Regulation of the legal profession and access to law, Report commissioned by the International Association of Legal Expenses Insurance (RIAD), SEO Economic Research. Barendrecht, M. (2008). In Search of Microjustice: Five Basic Elements of a Dispute System. SSRN. Barendrecht, M. (2009). "Best Practices for an Affordable and Sustainable Dispute System: A Toolbox for Microjustice." SSRN. Barendrecht, M. (2009). Providing Microjustice: Understanding the Market for Justice, SSRN. Barendrecht, M., K. Bolt, et al. (2006). "Appeal Procedures: Evaluation and Reform." Barendrecht, M. and B. R. De Vries (2006). "Fitting the Forum to the Fuss with Sticky Defaults: Failure on the Market for Dispute Resolution Services? ." Cardozo Journal of Conflict Resolution 7(1). Barendrecht, M., P. Kamminga, et al. (2008). Priorities for the Justice System: Responding to the Most Urgent Legal Problems of Individuals, SSRN. Barendrecht, M. and P. Van Nispen (2008). Microjustice, SSRN. Barendrecht, M. and J. H. Verdonschot (2008). Objective Criteria: Facilitating Dispute Resolution by Information About Going Rates of Justice, SSRN. Beenstock, M. and Y. Haitovsky (2004). "Does the appointment of judges increase the output of the judiciary?" International Review of Law and Economics: 351-369. Beersma, B. and C. K. W. De Dreu (2003). "Social Motives in Integrative Negotiation: The Mediating Influence of Procedural Fairness." Social Justice Research 16(3): 217-239. Ben-Shahar, O. and J. Pottow (2006). "On the Stickiness of Default Rules." Florida State University Law Review 33. Bendersky, C. (2003). "Organizational dispute resolution systems: A complementarities model." The Academy of Management Review: 643-656. Bingham, L. B. (2008). "Designing Justice: Legal Institutions and Other Systems for Managing Conflict." Ohio St. J. on Disp. Resolution. Bordone, R. C. (2008). Dispute System Design: An Introduction. Botero, J. C., R. La Porta, et al. (2003). The World Bank Research Observer 18(1): 61-88. Botero, J. C., R. La Porta, et al. (2003). "Judicial Reform." The World Bank Research Observer 18(1): 61- 88. Bovbjerg, R. R., F. A. Sloan, et al. (1989). "Valuing Life and Limb in Tort: Scheduling “Pain and Suffering”." 83 NW. U. L. (REV. 908. ). Bovens, M. (2005). Public accountability. The Oxford Handbook of Public Management. E. Ferlie, L. Lynne and C. Pollitt. Oxford, Oxford University Press: 182-208. Bovens, M. (2007). "Analysing and Assessing Accountability: A Conceptual Framework." European Law Journal 13(4): 447-468. Brousseau, E. and E. Raynaud (2006). The Economics of Private Institutions: An Introduction to the Dynamics of Institutional Frameworks and to the Analysis of Multilevel Multi-Type Governance, SSRN. Brunet, E., R. E. Speidel, et al. (2006). Arbitration Law in America: a Critical Assessment, Cambridge University Press. Buck, A., P. Pleasence, et al. (2008). "Do Citizens Know How to Deal with Legal Issues? Some Empirical Insights." Journal of Social Policy 37(04): 661-681. ���� � Buscaglia, E. and M. Dakolias (1999). Comparative International Study of Court Performance Indicators. A Descriptive and Analytical Account., The World Bank. Buscaglia, E. and J. van Dijk (2003). Controlling organized crime and corruption in the public sector. Forum on crime and society, United Nations Pubns. 3. Cabrillo, F. and S. Fitzpatrick (2008). The Economics of Courts and Litigation. Cheltenham, UK, Edward Elgar. Calabresi, G. (1999). A common law for the age of statutes, Lawbook Exchange Ltd. Cappeletti, M. and B. Garth (1978). "Access to Justice: The Newest Wave in the Worldwide Movement to Make Rights Effective." Buffalo Law Review 27(181). Carothers, T., Ed. (2006). Promoting the Rule of Law Abroad: In Search of Knowledge. Washington D.C., Carnegie Endowment for International Peace. Carothers, T. (2007). "The "Sequencing" Fallacy." Journal of Democracy 18(1). Carraro, C., C. Marchiori, et al. (2006). "Advances in Negotiation Theory: Bargaining, Coalitions and Fairness." World. Choi, S. J., G. M. Gulati, et al. (2009). "Are Judges Overpaid? A Skeptical Response to the Judicial Salary Debate." The Journal of Legal Analysis 1(1): 47-117. Cialdini, R. B. (2007). "Descriptive Social Norms As Underappreciated Sources Of Social Control." Psychometrika Vol. 72(No. 2): 6. Cialdini, R. B. and N. J. Goldstein (2004). "Social Influence: Compliance and Conformity." Annual Review of Psychology 55: 591-621. Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor (2008). Making the Law Work for Everyone. II Working Group Reports. Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor (2008). Making the Law Work for Everyone. I. Cooter, R., S. Marks, et al. (1982). "Bargaining in the Shadow of the Law: A Testable Model of Strategic Behavior " The Journal of Legal Studies 11(2): 225-251 Costantino, C. A. and C. Sickles Merchant (1996). Designing conflict management systems. San Francisco, Jossey-Bass. Coumarelos, C., Z. Wei, et al. (2006). Justice made to measure : NSW legal needs survey in disadvantaged areas, Law and Justice Foundation of New South Wales. Cousins, B., T. Cousins, et al. (2005). "Will formalising property rights reduce poverty in South Africa’s ‘second economy’ ?Questioning the mythologies of Hernando de Soto." Plaas Policy Brief 18. Couyoumdjian, J. P. (2008). "An Expert at Work: Revisiting Jeremy Bentham's Proposals on Codification." Kyklos 61(4): 503-519. Cowan, R. and D. Foray (1997). "The economics of codification and the diffusion of knowledge." Industrial and Corporate Change 6(3): 595-622. Curran, B. A. (1977). The Legal Needs of the Public: The Final Report of A National Survey. Chicago, American Bar Foundation. Currie, A. (2005). "A National Survey of The Civil Justice Problems of Low And Moderate Income Canadians: Incidence and Patterns." Retrieved 04/12/2007, 2007, from http://cfcj- fcjc.org/docs/2006/currie-en.pdf. Currie, J. and W. B. MacLeod (2008). "First Do No Harm? Tort Reform and Birth Outcomes*." Quarterly Journal of Economics 123(2): 795-830. Dam, K. w. (2006). The Law-Growth Nexus: The Rule of Law and Economic Development. Washington D.C., Brookings Institution Press. Davies, L. (2004). "Building a civic culture post-conflict." London Review of Education 2(3): 229-244. Davis, K. E. and M. J. Trebilcock (2008). "The Relationship Between Law and Development: Optimists versus Skeptics." American Journal of Comparative Law, Vol. 56, No. 4, 2008. Davis, K. E. and M. J. Trebilcock (2008). "The Relationship Between Law and Development: Optimists versus Skeptics." American Journal of Comparitive Law 56. Dawson, R. (2005). Developing knowledge-based client relationships: leadership in professional services, Butterworth-Heinemann. De Soto, H. (2000). The Mystery of Captal; Why Capitalism Triumphs in the West and Fails Everywhere Else. New York. Deininger, K. W. (2003). Land Policies for Growth and Poverty Reduction, A World Bank Publication. Deutsch, M., P. T. Coleman, et al. (2006). The Handbook of Conflict Resolution: Theory and Practice. San Francisco. ���� � Dhillon, A., J. Rigolini, et al. (2006). Development and the interaction of enforcement institutions. World Bank Policy Research Working Paper Dignan, T. (2004). Legal need in Northern Ireland: Literature Review, Northern Ireland Legal Services Commission. Djankov, S., R. La Porta, et al. (2003). "Courts." Quarterly Journal of Economics(May). Durand-Lasserve, A. and H. Selod (2007). The formalisation of urban land tenure in developing countries. The World Bank Urban Research Symposium Washington DC. Eisenberg, T. and G. P. Miller (2006). The Flight from Arbitration: An Empirical Study of Ex Ante Arbitration Clauses in Publicly-Held Companies' Contracts, SSRN. Fabri, M. and P. M. Langbroek (2000). The Challenge of Change for Judicial Systems: Developing a Public Administration Perspective, IOS Press. Fafchamps, M. (2004). Market institutions in Sub-Saharan Africa: theory and evidence, MIT Press. Fafchamps, M. and S. Lund (2003). "Risk-sharing networks in rural Philippines." Journal of Development Economics 71: 261-287. Fenske, J. E. (2009). Land Tenure and Investment Incentives: Evidence from West Africa, SSRN. Field, E. (2005). "Property Rights and Investment in Urban Slums." Journal of the European Economic Association 3(2-3): 279-290. Field, E. (2007). "Entitled to Work: Urban Property Rights and Labor Supply in Peru*." Quarterly Journal of Economics 122(4): 1561-1602. Fisher, R., W. Ury, et al. (1991). Getting to yes: negotiating agreement without giving in. New York, N.Y., Penguin Books. Fitzpatrick, D. (2005). "'Best Practice' Options for the Legal Recognition of Customary Tenure." Development and Change 36(3): 449-475. Fon, V. and F. Parisi (2006). "Judicial precedents in civil law systems: A dynamic analysis." International Review of Law and Economics 26(4): 519-535. Fon, V. and F. Parisi (2007). "On the optimal specificity of legal rules." Journal of Institutional Economics 3(02): 147-164. Galanter, M. (1974). "Why the "Haves" Come Out Ahead: Speculations on the Limits of Legal Change." Law and Society Review 9(1): 165-230. Galanter, M. (2004). "The Vanishing Trial: An Examination of Trials and Related Matters in Federal and State Courts." Journal of Empirical Legal Studies 1(3): 459-570. Galiani, S. and E. Schargrodsky (2009). Property rights for the poor: Effects of land titling. Ronald Coase Institute Working Paper Series. Genn, D. H. and S. Beinart (1999). Paths to Justice. What people do and think about going to law? Oxford, Hart Publishing. Genn, D. H. and A. Paterson (2001). Paths to Justice Scotland. What People in Scotland Do and Think About Going to Law. Oxford, Hart Publishing. Genn, H. (2008). Hamlyn Lectures George, J. P. (2006). "Access to justice, costs and legal aid." American Journal of Comparative Law(Fall 2006). Ghei, N. and F. Parisi (2004). "Adverse Selection and Moral Hazard in Forum Shopping: Conflicts Law as Spontaneous Order." Cardozo Law Review 25(4). Goldberg, S. B. and M. L. Shaw (2007). "The Secrets of Successful (and Unsuccessful) Mediators Continued: Studies Two and Three." Negotiation Journal 23(4): 393-418. Goldstein, M. and C. Udry (2008). "The Profits of Power: Land Rights and Agricultural Investment in Ghana." Journal of Political Economy 116(6): 981-1022. Golub, S. (2003). Beyond Rule of Law Orthodoxy: The Legal Empowerment Alternative, Carnegie Endowment for International Peace. Gramatikov, M. (2008). A Framework for Measuring the Costs of Paths to Justice, SSRN. Gramatikov, M. (2008). Multiple Justiciable Events in Bulgaria. Reaching Further: New Approaches to the Delivery of Legal Services. L. S. R. Centre. London: 22. Gramatikov, M., M. Barendrecht, et al. (2008). Measuring the Costs and Quality of Paths to Justice: Contours of a Methodology. Reaching Further: New Approaches to the Delivery of Legal Services, London, Legal Services Research Center. Greif, A. (2006). Institutions and the path to the modern economy: Lessons from medieval trade, Cambridge University Press. ���� � Hacker, D. (2008). "A legal field in action: the case of divorce arrangements in Israel." International Journal of Law in Context 4(01): 1-33. Hadfield, G. (2008). "Legal Barriers to Innovation." Regulation 31(3): 14-21. Hadfield, G. and E. Talley (2006). "On Public versus Private Provision of Corporate Law." JOURNAL OF LAW ECONOMICS AND ORGANIZATION 22(2): 414. Hadfield, G. K. (2000). "The Price of Law: How the Market for Lawyers Distorts the Justice System." Michigan Law Review 98(4): 953-1006. Hadfield, G. K. (2008). "The levers of legal design: Institutional determinants of the quality of law." Journal of Comparative Economics: 43-73. Haggard, S., A. MacIntyre, et al. (2008). "Rule of law and economic development." Annual Review of Political Science 11: 205-34. Hammergren, L. A. (2007). Envisioning Reform: Improving Judicial Performance in Latin America, Pennsylvania State University Press. Henderson, K., A. Shah, et al. (2004). "Regional Best Practices: Enforcement of Judgments: Lessons from Latin America." IFES, Rule of Law Paper Series, WashingtonDC. Hesselink, M. W. (2006). The politics of a European civil code, Kluwer Law International. Hirshleifer, J. (2000). "The Macrotechnology of Conflict." Journal Of Conflict Resolution 44(6): 773-792. Hirshleifer, J. (2001). The Dark Side of the Force: Economic Foundations of Conflict Theory. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Hollander-Blumoff, R. and T. R. Tyler (2008). "Procedural Justice in Negotiation: Procedural Fairness, Outcome Acceptance, and Integrative Potential." Law & Social Inquiry 33(2): 473-500. Husted, B. W. and R. Folger (2004). "Fairness and Transaction Costs: The Contribution of Organizational Justice Theory to an Integrative Model of Economic Organization." ORGANIZATION SCIENCE 15(6): 719-729. Islam, R. (2003). Institutional Reform and the Judiciary: Which Way Forward? World Bank Policy Research Working Paper Jappelli, T., M. Pagano, et al. (2005). "Courts and Banks: Effects of Judicial Enforcement on Credit Markets." Journal of Money, Credit, and Banking 37(2): 223-244. Jensen, E. G. (2002). The Rule of Law and Judicial Reform: The Political Economy of Diverse Institutional Patterns and Reformers’ Responses. Beyond Common Knowledge: Empirical Approaches to the Rule of Law. . E. G. Jensen and T. C. Heller, Stanford University Press. Jia, W. (2002). Chinese Mediation and Its Cultural Foundation. Chinese Conflict Management and Resolution. G.-M. Chen and R. Ma. Westport, Ablex Publishing. Kaplow, L. (1992). "Rules versus standards: an economic analysis." Duke Law Journal: 557-629. Katsh, E. E., M. E. Katsh, et al. (2001). Online Dispute Resolution: Resolving Conflicts in Cyberspace. New York, John Wiley & Sons, Inc. . Kaufmann, D. (2003). Rethinking Governance: Empirical Lessons Challenge Orthodoxy, SSRN. Kennett, W. A. (2000). Enforcement of judgments in Europe, Oxford University Press. Kerber, W. and S. Grundmann (2006). "An optional European contract law code: Advantages and disadvantages." European Journal of Law and Economics 21(3): 215-236. Klerman, D. (2007). "Jurisdictional competition and the evolution of the common law." University of Chicago Law Review 74: 1179. Knight, J. (1992). Institutions and Social Conflict, Cambridge University Press. Korobkin, R. B. (1998). "The status quo bias and contract default rules." Cornell Law Review 83. Korobkin, R. B. and J. W. Doherty (2007). Who Wins in Settlement Negotiations?, SSRN. Lande, J. (2005). "The Promise and Perils of Collaborative Law." Dispute Resolution Magazine 12. Lande, J. (2008). "Developing Better Lawyers and Lawyering Practices: Introduction to the Symposium on Innovative Models of Lawyering." Journal of Dispute Resolution(1). Landes, W. M. and R. A. Posner (1979). "Adjudication as a private good." Journal of Legal Studies 8: 235. Lanjouw, J. O. and P. I. Levy (2002). "Untitled: a study of formal and informal property rights in urban Ecuador." Economic Journal: 986-1019. Lewicki, R. J., D. M. Saunders, et al. (2006). Negotiation Boston, McGraw Hill/Irwin. Lind, E. A. and T. R. Tyler (1988). The Social Psychology of Procedural Justice. New York, Plenum Pub Corp. López de Silanes, F. (2002). "The politics of legal reform." Economía: 91-136. ���� � MacKenzie, D. L. (2006). What Works in Corrections: Reducing the Recidivism of Offenders and Delinquents, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. MacLeod, W. B. (2007). "Reputations, Relationships, and Contract Enforcement." Journal of Economic Literature 45(3): 595-628. Maru, V. (2006). "Between law and society: paralegals and the provision of justice services in Sierra Leone and worldwide." Yale J. Int'l L. 31: 427. Masser, A. L. (2009). Measurement Methodologies for Legal Empowerment of the Poor. UNDP Bureau of Development Policy. Menkel-Meadow, C. (1996). "The Trouble with the Adversarial System in a Postmodern, Multicultural World." Wm. & Mary L. Rev. 38: 5. Messick, R. (1999). Reducing Court Delays: Five lessons from the United States. PREM notes, The World Bank. Michelson, E. (2007). "Climbing the Dispute Pagoda: Grievances and Appeals to the Official Justice System in Rural China." American Sociological Review 72: 459-485. Michelson, E. (2008). "Justice from Above or Justice from Below? Popular Strategies for Resolving Grievances in Rural China." China Quarterly 193: 43-64. Miller, G. P. (2008) "Preliminary Judgments." Volume, DOI: Mnookin, R. H. (2003). "Strategic Barriers to Dispute Resolution: A Comparison of Bilateral and Multilateral Negotiations." Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics JITE 159: 199-220. Mnookin, R. H. and L. Kornhauser (1978). "Bargaining in the Shadow of the Law: The Case of Divorce." Yale Law Journal 88: 950. Mnookin, R. H., S. R. Peppet, et al. (2000). Beyond Winning, Negotiating Deals To Create Value In Deals And Disputes. Cambridge Mass., The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. Mnookin, R. H., L. Susskind, et al. (1999). Negotiating on Behalf of Others, Sage Publications. Moffitt, M. L., R. C. Bordone, et al. (2005). The Handbook of Dispute Resolution, Jossey-Bass. Moore, C., W. (2003). The mediation process–Practical strategies for resolving conflict, . San Francisco, Jossey-Bass. Muthoo, A. (1999). Bargaining Theory with Applications. Cambridge U.K., Cambridge University Press. Muthoo, A. (2000). "A Non-Technical Introduction to Bargaining Theory." World Economics 1(2): 145-166. Nisenbaum, S. (2009). Negotiation and the Shadow of Law. Handbook on Building Cultures of Peace. J. De Rivera: 245-257. North, D. C., J. J. Wallis, et al. (2009). Violence and Social Orders; A Conceptual Framework for Interpreting Recorded Human History. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. O'Hara, E. A. and L. E. Ribstein (2000). "From politics to efficiency in choice of law." The University of Chicago Law Review: 1151-1232. O Shea, P. and C. Rickett (2006). "In Defence of Consumer Law: The Resolution of Consumer Disputes." Sydney Law Review 28: 139. Oetzel, J. G. and S. Ting-Toomey (2006). The SAGE handbook of conflict communication. Thousand Oaks, SAGE. Otto, J. M. (2009). "Rule of Law Promotion, Land Tenure and Poverty Alleviation: Questioning the Assumptions of Hernando de Soto." Hague Journal on the Rule of Law 1(01): 173-194. Ouchi, W. G. (1980). "Markets, Bureaucracies, and Clans." Administrative Science Quarterly: 129-141. Parisi, F. (2000). 9500 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law. Encyclopedia of Law and Economics. B. Bouckaert and G. De Geest. Cheltenham, Edward Elgar. V The Economics of Crime and Litigation. Parker, C. (1999). Just lawyers, Oxford University Press. Payne, G., A. Durand-Lasserve, et al. (2007). Social and economic impacts of land titling programmes in urban and peri-urban areas: A review of the literature. The Worldbank Urban Research Symposium, Washington DC. Pearce, R. G. (2004). "Redressing Inequality in the Market for Justice: Why Access to Lawyers Will Never Solve the Problem and Why Rethinking the Role of Judges Will Help." Fordham Law Review 73. Penal Reform International and Bloom Legal Clinic of the Northwestern School of Law (2007). Access to Justice in Africa and Beyond: Making the Rule of Law a Reality, Ntl Inst for Trial Advocacy. Peysner, J., M. Seneviratne, et al. (2005). The management of civil cases: the courts and post-Woolf landscape, Department for Constitutional Affairs. Pillutla, M. M. and J. K. Murnighan (2003). "Fairness in Bargaining." Social Justice Research,: 22. ���� � Polinsky, A. M. and S. Shavell (2000). "The Economic Theory of Public Enforcement of Law." Journal of Economic Literature 38(1): 45-76. Ponzetto, G. A. M. and P. A. Fernandez (2008). "Case Law versus Statute Law: An Evolutionary Comparison." The Journal of Legal Studies 37(2): 379-430. Posner, E. A. (2003). "Four Economic Perspectives on American Labor Law and the Problem of Social Conflict." Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics JITE 159: 101-116. Posner, R. A. (1993). "What Do Judges and Justices Maximize? (The Same Thing Everybody Else Does)." Supreme Court Economic Review: 1-41. Posner, R. A. and E. B. Rasmusen (1999). "Creating and Enforcing Norms, with Special Reference to Sanctions." International Review of Law and Economics 19: 14. Rakodi, C. and C. Leduka (2004). Informal Land Delivery Processes and Access to Land for the Poor: A Comparative Study of Six African Cities. Policy Briefs, International Development Department, University of Birmingham. Ramírez, F., D. Suárez, et al. (2007). The Worldwide Rise of Human Rights Education. School Knowledge in Comparative and Historical Perspective. A. Benavot, C. Braslavsky and N. Truong: 35-52. Rao, P. K. (2003). The Economics of Transaction Costs; Theory, Methods, and Applications. New York, Palgrave MacMillan. Ray, B. (2009). Extending the Shadow of the Law: Using Hybrid Mechanisms to Develop Constitutional Norms in Socioeconomic Rights Cases: 2. Relis, T. (2002). "Civil Litigation from Litigants' Perspectives: What We Know and What We Don't Know About the Litigation Experience of Individual Litigants." Studies in Law, Politics and Society 25: 151-212. Resnik, J. (1982). "Managerial judges." Harvard Law Review 96: 374. Rhode, D. L. (2004). Access to Justice. New York, Oxford University Press. Ringer, T. (2007). "Development, Reform, and the Rule of Law: Some Prescriptions for a Common Understanding of the 'Rule of Law' and its Place in Development Theory and Practice." Yale Human Rights and Development Law Journal 10(1). Ross, L. (1995). Reactive Devaluation in Negotiation and Conflict Resolution. New York, W.W. Norton. . Sabates-Wheeler, R., S. Devereux, et al. (2009). "Taking the Long View: What Does a Child Focus Add to Social Protection?" IDS Bulletin 40(1): 109-119. Sandefur, R. L. (2006). Lawyer, Nonlawyer and Pro Se Representation and Trial and Hearing Outcomes, SSRN. Sappington, D. E. M. (2005). "Regulating service quality: a survey." Journal of Regulatory Economics 27(2): 123-154. Schauer, F. (2008). "Why precedent in law (and elsewhere) is not totally (or even substantially) about analogy." Perspectives on Psychological Science 3(6): 454-460. Setel, P. W., S. B. Macfarlane, et al. (2007). "A scandal of invisibility: making everyone count by counting everyone." The Lancet 370(9598): 1569-1577. Shavell, S. (2004). Foundations of Economic Analysis of Law Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press. Shell, R. (2006). Bargaining for Advantage:Negotiation Strategies for Rational People. London, Penguin Books. Sherwin, E. (2006). "Judges as Rulemakers." The University of Chicago Law Review: 919-931. Smits, J. M. (2008). "The Draft-Common Frame of Reference (CFR) for a European Private Law: Fit for Purpose?" Maastricht Journal of European and Comparative Law 15: 145-148. Stephen, F. and J. Love (1999). Regulation of law firms. Encyclopedia of Law and Economics. G. De Geest and B. Bouckaert. London, Edgar Elgar: 987-1017. Sternlight, J. R. (2005). "Creeping mandatory arbitration: Is it just?" Stanford Law Review 57: 1631. Sternlight, J. R. (2007). "In Defense of Mandatory Arbitration (If Imposed on the Company)." Nevada Law Journal 8. Stiglitz, J. (2000). Handbook of Economics of the Public Sector. Stiglitz, J. E. (1999). "Knowledge as a global public good." Global public goods 1(9): 308-326. Sunstein, C. R. (1999). One case at a time: Judicial minimalism on the Supreme Court, Harvard University Press. Sunstein, C. R. (2007). "Incompletely Theorized Agreements in Constitutional Law." Social Research: An International Quarterly of Social Sciences 74(1): 1-24. �� � � Sunstein, C. R. (2008). Beyond Judicial Minimalism, SSRN. Szreter, S. (2007). "The right of registration: development, identity registration, and social security—a historical perspective." World Development 35(1): 67-86. Tamanaha, B. Z. (2008). A Concise Guide to the Rule of Law. Florence Workshop on The Rule of Law. N. Walker and G. Palombella, Hart Publishing Company. Tamanaha, B. Z. (2009). The Primacy of Society and the Failure of Law and Development, SSRN. Tamanaha, B. Z. (2009). "The Primacy of Society and the Failure of Law and Development." SSRN eLibrary. Trubek, D. M., A. Sarat, et al. (1983). "The Costs of Ordinary Litigation." UCLA Law Review 31: 72-123. Tullock, G. (1980). Trials on Trial: The Pure Theory of Legal Procedure. New York, Columbia University Press. Tyler, T. R. (1997). Citizen Discontent with Legal Procedures: A Social Science Perspective on Civil Procedure Reform. Civil Procedure Reform in Comparative Context, Florence, Italy, New York University. Tyler, T. R. (2006). "Legitimacy and legitimation." Annual Review of Psychology 57: 375-400. Tyler, T. R. (2006). Why people obey the law. Princeton Princeton University Press. Tyler, T. R. (2007). Psychology and the Design of Legal Institutions. Nijmegen, Wolf Legal Publishers. Ury, W. L., J. M. Brett, et al. (1988). Getting disputes resolved: Designing systems to cut the costs of conflict. San Francisco, Jossey Bass. Van den Berg, M. and P. Kamminga (2006). "Optimising Contracting for Alliances in Infrastructure Projects." International Construction Law Review 23(1). Van Rooij, B. (2007). Bringing Justice to the Poor, Bottom-up Legal Development Cooperation Annual meeting of the The Law and Society Association Berlin, Germany. Van Velthoven, B. J. and M. Ter Voert (2004). Geschilbeslechtingsdelta 2003. Den Haag, WODC. Van Zeeland, C., P. Kamminga, et al., Eds. (2007). A Code of Conduct for Negotiating Personal Injury Claims: Structuring the Shadow of Tort Law. Tilburg University Legal Studies Working Paper. Varian, H. R. (1998). Markets for information goods. Velikonja, U. (2009). "Making Peace and Making Money: Economic Analysis of the Market for Mediators in Private Practice." Albany Law Review 72. Verdonschot, J. H. (2009). Delivering Objective Criteria: Sources of Law and the Relative Value of Neutral Information for Dispute Resolution, SSRN. Walker, D. and K. Hampson (2003). Enterprise networks, partnering and alliancing. Procurement Strategies: A Relationship-Based Approach. D. Walker and K. Hampson, Blackwell Science Ltd. Wall, J. A., Jr., J. B. Stark, et al. (2001). "Mediation: A Current Review and Theory Development." Journal Of Conflict Resolution 45(3): 370-391. Wall Jr, J. A. and R. R. Callister (1995). "Conflict and Its Management." Journal of Management 21(3): 515. Wall Jr, J. A. and S. Chan-Serafin (2009). "Processes in civil case mediations." Conflict Resolution Quarterly 26(3): 261-291. Walton, R. and R. McKersie (1965). A Behavioral Theory of Labor Negotiations. Beverly Hills, Sage Publications. Ware, S. J. (2004). "Arbitration Clauses, Jury-Waiver Clauses and Other Contractual Waivers of Constitutional Rights." Law and Contemporary Problems 67. Welsh, N. W. (2004). "Perceptions of Fairness in Negotiation Symposium: the Emerging Interdisciplinary Canon of Negotiation Fairness " Marquette Law Review 87. Williamson, O. E. (1981). "The Economics of Organization: The Transaction Cost Approach." American Journal of Sociology 87(3): 548. Williamson, O. E. (1999). "Public and private bureaucracies: a transaction cost economics perspectives." J Law Econ Organ 15(1): 306-342. Williamson, O. E. (2005). "The Economics of Governance." American Economic Review 95(2): 1-18. Wissler, R. L. (2004). "The effectiveness of court-connected dispute resolution in civil cases." Conflict Resolution Quarterly 22(1-2): 55-88. Woolf, H. (1996). Access to Justice Final Report to the Lord Chancellor on the Civil Justice System in England and Wales. London, Hmso Books. �� � � Wormith, J. S., R. Althouse, et al. (2007). "The Rehabilitation and Reintegration of Offenders: The Current Landscape and Some Future Directions for Correctional Psychology." Criminal Justice and Behavior 34(7): 879-892. Yeazell, S. (2008). Transparency for Civil Settlements: NASDAQ for Lawsuits?, SSRN. Zuckerman, A. (1999). Assessment of Cost and Delay - a Multi-National - Perspective. Procedural Law in the Threshold of a New Millenium, Wien, University of Wien. Zuckerman, A. A. S., S. Chiarloni, et al. (1999). Civil justice in crisis: comparative perspectives of civil procedure, Oxford University Press. work_65d5ndww4jb3pg4yowyxfcjtku ---- Pipeline Spills and Indigenous Energy Justice sustainability Review Pipeline Spills and Indigenous Energy Justice Ranjan Datta * and Margot A. Hurlbert The Johnson Shoyama Graduate School of Public Policy (JSGS), University of Regina, Regina, SK S4P 4V5, Canada; Margot.Hurlbert@uregina.ca * Correspondence: Ranjan.datta@usask.ca Received: 7 November 2019; Accepted: 16 December 2019; Published: 19 December 2019 ����������������� Abstract: The Canadian provinces of Alberta and Saskatchewan transport their energy resources by pipeline to the eastern and western seaboards, and south into the United States. The used pipeline infrastructure reshapes the landscape and affects sustainability of the environment, traditional Indigenous livelihoods, and drinking water, particularly when spills and leaks occur. This scoping review is focused on Indigenous sustainability issues in relation to surrounding pipeline spills/leaks, impacts on drinking water and Indigenous communities in Western Canada. We found that Indigenous communities are particularly vulnerable to pipeline leaks, and have limited capacity to mitigate them. Strategic decisions need to be made about the management of pipeline leaks. For building Indigenous energy justice, the findings of this paper suggest that Indigenous-led databases, programs to monitor and assess impacts, report leaks, and funding of community-based participatory action research are required. Keywords: energy; Indigenous drinking water; Indigenous; pipeline spills; scoping review; sustainability 1. Introduction The Western Canadian provinces of Alberta and Saskatchewan significantly rely on oil pipelines’ revenue, dependent on the transport of their energy resources by pipeline to the eastern and western seaboards, and south into the United States. Pipeline infrastructure reshapes the landscape and impacts sustainability of the environment, traditional Indigenous livelihoods, and drinking water, when spills and leaks occur. The purpose of this paper is to provide Indigenous communities, particularly those communities of northern Alberta and Saskatchewan, with new tools that can help them make strategic choices about pipeline leak management to enhance their energy justice to pipeline leaks. Indigenous knowledge has important lineages in energy sustainability, as it includes culturally distinctive ways of knowing specifics to societies, with long histories of interaction with their natural surroundings. For Indigenous people, the term sustainability is part of their everyday life, which connects spiritually and relationally; acting sustainably means giving, not taking the Earth’s natural resources and is defined by an ethic of making decisions in respect of Earth’s resources that will not hamper the access to these resources for the next seven generations [1]. Indigenous knowledge includes traditional ways of knowing and doing in sustainably managing very complex ecosystems [2]. In the dramatic transition of energy and water management regimes over the last few decades, Indigenous knowledge has received little recognition, and Indigenous histories and perspectives are rarely valued as significant data to the sustainable contemporary management of water and energy resources [3]. For understanding the concept of sustainability in energy and drinking water access for Indigenous people, this paper reports on a scoping review of critical issues in sustainability, particularly energy pipelines and their impact on Indigenous peoples’ drinking water access. For instance, how is the concept of Indigenous sustainability and Indigenous energy justice affected through colonial Sustainability 2020, 12, 47; doi:10.3390/su12010047 www.mdpi.com/journal/sustainability http://www.mdpi.com/journal/sustainability http://www.mdpi.com https://orcid.org/0000-0001-7511-6583 https://orcid.org/0000-0003-3825-8413 http://www.mdpi.com/2071-1050/12/1/47?type=check_update&version=1 http://dx.doi.org/10.3390/su12010047 http://www.mdpi.com/journal/sustainability Sustainability 2020, 12, 47 2 of 9 energy management policy and practices? This paper reports on a scoping review of energy issues surrounding pipeline spills/leaks, and impacts on drinking water and Indigenous communities in Western Canada. This paper first suggests that the researchers need to explore past leak impacts on Indigenous communities’ water, agriculture, and challenges in current risk management processes and regulations; and secondly, provide recommendations to build sustainability in Indigenous energy practice from and within Indigenous people and their perspectives. 2. Scoping Methodological Framework of Study Our scoping review in this paper was used according to our keywords listed in Table 1. Drawing from a scoping method logical framework, this paper focused on Indigenous sustainability through Indigenous energy and water [4,5]. A scoping method logical framework is “a form of knowledge synthesis that addresses an exploratory research question aimed at mapping key concepts, types of evidence, and gaps in research related to a defined area or field by systematically searching, selecting, and synthesizing existing knowledge” [6]. In this paper, we used the scoping method logical framework with a comprehensive assessment of the literature. The present scoping review was guided by keywords listed in Table 1. The goal was to evaluate the extent to which Indigenous sustainability issues have been considered in these studies, and to discuss their conclusion. Thematic key words were reviewed from the online databases prior to search. The authors searched for intersections of the issues of pipeline spills/leaks and Indigenous conceptualizations of sustainability. Search databases were used with a wide range of disciplines, which included Web of Science (multidisciplinary, 2008–present) and Google Scholar. Thematic keywords used for searching are included in Table 1. Table 1. Keywords used for literature search. #1 Pipeline Spills/Leaks Pipeline Spills, OR Leaks OR Pipeline Breaks OR Pipeline #2 Indigenous Energy Indigenous Meanings of Energy OR Energy Management OR Indigenous Energy #3 Drinking water Crisis Drinking water quality OR water crisis OR drinkable water protection OR safe water OR water OR sustainable water supply OR fresh water OR water OR water supply #4 Indigenous Communities Indigenous people OR Indigenous OR Unban Indigenous OR Reserve Indigenous OR Aboriginal OR Native(s) OR Indigenous people OR First Nations OR Métis OR Inuit Or Inuk #5 Environmental Impacts Environmental Impacts OR Environmental Harms OR Environmental Injustice #6 Health Impacts Spiritual health wellness OR well-being OR mental health OR social health #7 Challenges Challenges in solution OR Barriers #8 Canada Canada OR Indigenous areas in North America #1 #5 AND #1 AND #4 3. Overview Findings from Selected Studies We found a total of 220 articles from our overall search with 46 from the bibliographic searching process (i.e., according to the key words, authors’ names, the titles of the works), and 174 from grey literature. 35 articles matched with our thematic keywords, title, and abstract (i.e., Table 1: Keywords #1, 2, 3, and 4); however, 21 studies did not meet the second-level required criteria, leaving a total of 19 articles matching for the final scoping review. Focusing on our search findings, we divided our result sections into five subsections including: first, thematic analysis and study findings; second, lack of Indigenous engagement in energy management and pipelines; third, impact of pipelines on Indigenous drinking water quality; fourth, pipeline spills/leaks and impacts; and finally, recommendations. Sustainability 2020, 12, 47 3 of 9 4. Thematic Analysis from Study Findings The findings of reviewed articles were grouped under the following key themes: (a) Challenges in Indigenous Engagement concerning Energy and Pipelines; (b) Impact of Pipelines on Indigenous Drinking Water Quality; (c) Pipeline Spills/Leaks and Impacts on Indigenous people. Our scoping review focused on a systematic approach to find Indigenous sustainability-related information on Indigenous environmental issues associated with pipelines spills in Indigenous communities in Canada and North America. Our review found 19 closely relevant articles from the initial pool of 220 articles. The focusing points in this review were the literature on pipeline spills, impacts of drinking water, and agriculture, and health in Indigenous communities in Canada. None of the articles in the sample used a decolonizing approach on pipeline leaks and energy management, or an approach that would privilege Indigenous knowledge and perspectives surrounding sustainability. During our scoping review, we also focused on researchers who emphasised the Indigenous communities’ knowledge and values, the Calls for Action from the Truth and Reconciliation Commission, and Indigenous governments. The thematic analysis and study findings are summarized below. 4.1. Lack of Indigenous Engagement in Energy Management and Pipelines Most of the government and companies’ reports and assessments, as well as other reports by non-profit organizations, discussed governmental regulation and policy guidelines in Indigenous sustainability issues. Only three articles from the 19 articles critically discussed that there was insufficient focus on pipeline spills in Indigenous communities and impacts on Indigenous communities [7,8]. A recent report on Saskatchewan Indigenous communities shows that pipeline spills and their impact on Indigenous drinking water and agriculture are high in Indigenous communities compared to the national average, and more than 50% of Indigenous communities in reserve areas in Canada are at “high risk”. Two studies by Auston, and Wilke and Freeman [9,10] discuss that pipeline spills have more severe impact on rural Indigenous communities’ drinking water, agriculture, and traditional cultural practice with land than the other non-Indigenous communities do in urban areas. Another five articles discussed that governments’ lack of interest in Indigenous engagement as being a significant challenge for sustainable energy management [7–11]. Two studies [9,10] argue that because of the lack of Indigenous communities’ involvement in energy management, many Indigenous communities have suffered a number of negative impacts on their drinking water, health and surrounding environment. For instance, the Treaty 6 territory situated in Western Canada is one of the vulnerable parts of Canada including its Indigenous communities. According to the Assembly of First Nations, there are 81 long-term drinking water advisories (DWA) affecting more than 50 Indigenous communities across the country. As of August 6, 2018, there were 42 short-term DWAs in place, and there are more than 15,000 Indigenous people under Drinking Water Advisories in Saskatchewan [12]. Recent federal government activities have also become a major challenge for reducing pipeline leak impacts on many Indigenous communities [13]. A recent report of Canadian government initiatives for Indigenous energy management concludes that as of May 30, 2018, the current government in Canada confirmed it paid $4.5 billion to buy the Kinder Morgan pipeline; but there are many Indigenous communities currently living with high drinking water advisories [13]. There were 124 DWAs at the beginning of May 2018, and now the number has spiked to 174 advisories in the last couple of weeks. While in December 2017, the Parliamentary Budget Officer estimated the cost of ending boil water advisories by 2020 to be $3.2 billion, the Kinder Morgan pipeline crosses 1355 waterways, putting communities’ drinking water at risk. For instance, the Coldwater Indian Band, along with several other Indigenous nations, launched a legal challenge because the pipeline cuts right through the nation’s drinking water source. This study also claims that instead of allocating adequate funding to ensure clean water for First Nations and upholding the human right to water and sanitation, the Trudeau Sustainability 2020, 12, 47 4 of 9 government is committing $4.5 billion to bail out Kinder Morgan and ram through a pipeline project that puts the drinking water of Indigenous nations and municipalities at risk. This study also argues that the $4.5 billion Prime Minister Trudeau committed to bailing out Kinder Morgan could increase Indigenous communities’ capabilities to end boil water advisories in First Nations. No single article discussed Indigenous knowledge or perspectives in energy management and Indigenous decision-making opportunities in pipeline leaks management. However, there are two articles that show Indigenous engagement in energy and pipeline leaks management have been significantly missing historically [7,14]. Only two articles [3,15] strongly suggested including Indigenous communities and their traditional practices in sustainable energy management. 4.2. Impact of Pipelines on Indigenous Drinking Water Quality Seven articles discuss that pipeline leaks, DWA, and poor water quality are prominent in Indigenous communities. This is important for sustainability, given the impacts of pipeline spills/leaks on Indigenous people described below. These seven articles were coded regardless of the reason for source water deterioration, and included advisories issued due to the oil spill on the North Saskatchewan River [14–24]. If a groundwater source was believed to be under the direct impact of surface water, but there was insufficient treatment to deal with the direct influence of surface water, poor source water was coded and the article included. Silt being drawn into the treatment system by wells and changing the source water to a non-regulated water source was coded as poor source water. Pipeline development and its impacts on Indigenous communities is also a concerning factor for other parts of Canada. According to a recent report by Health Canada and British Columbia’s First Nations Health Authority, up to one-in-four people may not have clean drinking water on First Nations reserves [23]. This report argues that DWAs in Indigenous communities should not be a way of life in a country with an abundant water source. However, a lack of infrastructure, political will, and public solidarity causes such problems. This report also shows that on top of long-standing DWAs, the Trudeau government has actually approved a series of development projects that threaten important First Nations waterways such as Kinder Morgan’s Trans Mountain Expansion project and Enbridge’s Line 3 tar sands pipelines replacement project. Another three articles reported how pipeline leaks and their contamination of drinking water concerns specific pathogens in pipeline spills/leaks including serious health impacts from water [8,24–27]. Qualitative measures of impacts of pipeline spills/leaks in Indigenous drinking water were assessed in five other articles [19,21–24]. Two articles related to health risks from impacted drinking water [14,28]. In general, two of these suggested that there is a high risk in drinking water in Indigenous communities; however, they also suggested risks in drinking water differed according to province, water source, and other social and physical indicators [28]. 4.3. Pipeline Spills/Leaks and Impacts Six articles (three specifically from qualitative articles, the other three based from mixed methods articles) from 35 articles discussed pipeline spills/leaks [14–20]. For instance, the Wingrove (2012) study shows that there have been at least 10 pipelines leaks since 2011 in Alberta. Wingrove gave an example from the biggest pipeline spill (i.e., Plains Midstream pipeline spill near Little Buffalo) that leaked more than 4.5 million liters in April 2011, and another larger spill in December 2017 (i.e., from a Pengrowth Energy Corp. pipeline near Judy Creek, Alberta) where 1.9 million liters spilled. There were 12 major spills reported from 2008 to 2018 (Table 2), particularly in Saskatchewan and Alberta. Most of these oil spills are connected with either Indigenous surface water or their traditional food source, including Indigenous hunting and gathering. Sustainability 2020, 12, 47 5 of 9 Table 2. Major pipeline spills in between 2008–2017 in Canada, particularly in Saskatchewan and Alberta [14–20]. Major Pipeline Leaks 2008–2017 Amount (by L) July 2016 into the North Saskatchewan River. 250,000 L June 2016 into northwestern Alberta. 380,000 L July 2015 into near Fort McMurray, Alberta. 5 million L March 2015 into Northeast of Peace River, Alberta. 2.7 million L November 2014 into Red Earth Creek in northern Alberta. 60,000 L April 2014 into northwest of Slave Lake, Alberta. 70,000 L July 2013 into Cold Lake Air Weapons Range, Alberta. 1.5 million L May 2013 into Zama City, region of northern Alberta. 15 million L June 2012 into Red Deer River in central Alberta. 461,000 L May 2012 into near the Alberta–Northwest Territories boundary. 3.5 million L April 2011 into northern Alberta aboriginal community of Little Buffalo. 4.5 million L April 2007 into Glenavon, Saskatchewan. 990,000 L Two articles from 19 articles suggest that pipeline spills threaten ecosystems both ways (i.e., during spills and spill cleanup) [22–25]. For instance, the Todd (2017) study shows how spills can threaten the ecosystem in two ways: during spills, dangerous toxins mixed with surface which transferred to agricultural land, water, and wetland that contaminated whole ecosystems including human, animals, birds, and plants; during cleanup, physical cleanup (e.g., cleaning oil from surface) can have direct impacts of normal soil and water quality. Todd showed in how oil spills can damage native habitat and significantly reduce native species and foster invasive species. However, this study also suggests more research for making more concrete decisions on how spill removal from the surface can reduce habitat damage, and to understand the threats to native species and wildlife. Five articles show that pipeline spills not only impact on Indigenous people’s drinking water, but also have negative impacts on non-human species (such as birds and wildlife habitat including their food, water, shelter, and nesting areas) [8,26,27]. For instance, the Austen (2013) study shows that pipeline spills increase various environmental toxins in water, particularly aromatic hydrocarbons, and PAHs. According to Austen’s study, environmental toxins from pipeline spills (polycyclic aromatic hydrocarbons, or PAHs) can dissolve in water quickly and can kill non-human species including fish and other aquatic creatures. A number of studies [8,26–31] show that the non-human species, particularly fish and aquatic creatures, which live in the water for most or all of its lifetime, are more vulnerable to oil spills than other wildlife. The fish and aquatic creatures typically break down quickly and disappear. Other chemicals can have longer impact in the water and can make serious ongoing health effects for aquatic species that may appear after longer times, including after many months and years. Another study [14] suggests that environmental toxins (i.e., oil toxicity and its contaminants, or pollutants, and the oil itself) became less significant in human-centric politics. Pipeline spills have serious health outcomes interrelated with fear and poor drinking water in many Indigenous communities. For instance, an article [9] specifically discussed the weakness of governments and profit-oriented organization-led research by saying that environmental toxins from the pipeline spills have been poorly tracked, including carcinogens, gene mutagens, and endocrine disruptors. This study also suggests: (1) that the environmental toxins from the pipeline spills are directly connected with human cancer-causing compounds; (2) the official reports also found various toxins from spills at dangerous levels in waterways and deep-water; (3) the relationship between pipeline oil leaks and health impacts are highly significant. Further, a recent study by Wilke and Freeman [10] concluded that it is important to understand the relationship between pipeline oil leaks and air quality, as oil Sustainability 2020, 12, 47 6 of 9 spills or leaks can have significant impact on air quality. The air quality has an indirect connection with human chronic respiratory illnesses. Using data from a large electronic medical record representing more than 400,000 in primary care, Wilke and Freeman’s study suggests that 5935 patients are suffering with asthma. This study also claims that the connection between pipeline oil leaks and human health risks are high because of drinking water infections. 5. Discussion and Recommendations Our scoping review suggests there is a significant need for more academic and community-based research with Indigenous communities to understand sustainability issues from and within Indigenous perspectives. Indigenous knowledge needs to be understood through their participation and decision-making in energy management and drinking water pipeline leaks management and in identifying solutions. For understanding sustainability surrounding Indigenous energy and water, this review also suggests for the researcher’s critical focus to be on barriers and challenges in Indigenous communities (i.e., sufficient research funding to the community, Indigenous-led research, protecting drinking water, and their health). Although the number of related studies was very small in this scoping review, the studies reported reflect a wider range of research designs and findings by the Indigenous community. sustainability. For instance, while some research is emerging, there is very limited research on Indigenous communities’ perspectives and Indigenous knowledge on current pipeline development, and drinking water management. For understanding sustainability issues, this study suggests focusing on the redesign of research, and research within and from Indigenous community participants and academic researchers. The lack of cultural understanding among government and NGO researchers is also another significant challenge in Indigenous sustainability research [9–15] as well as improvement in increasing Indigenous communities’ active participation. Studies also recommend greater sample sizes from the community perspectives so that both academics and communities can better understand challenges from multiple perspectives. There is a need for Indigenous worldviews, Indigenous methodology, Indigenous research frameworks, from and within Indigenous community-based participatory research, that also can lead to community-based effective solutions. More research is also needed to understand government and non-governmental initiatives and their impact on Indigenous communities’ involvement in their energy management and sustainability [31–48]. For understanding sustainability issues, it is recommended that the significant gaps in the evidence of drinking water consequences related to pipeline leaks in Canadian Indigenous com-munities be addressed [31–37]. There are no systematic studies that focus on Indigenous rights, including access to drinking water and surrounding the health of women and minors in Indigenous communities. To move forward in better understanding sustainability through potential protection of Indigenous drinking water, their health, and their environment from pipeline spills in Canada, we make the following recommendations for understanding sustainability issues based on the scoping review: Community-Based Participatory Action Research (CBPAR). Studies suggested that Indigenous-led CBPAR can provide a better understanding from and within community perspectives on the oil spills, affecting assessment and protecting their drinking water and environment. Although there are significant needs for bridging among academic researchers, policy makers, community leaders, Indigenous Elders, Knowledge Keepers, government and companies; studies specifically suggested for centering Indigenous perspectives for building sustainability within and from Indigenous communities. Develop an Indigenous-Led Database. Studies argued that Indigenous communities, in most cases, do not have access to government and companies’ research information. Therefore, they do not know the impacts on their water, health, and environment. According to studies, the Indigenous-led database cannot only improve information access, but also can be helpful for government and companies to take meaningful, timely action from and within community people. Indigenous Elders, Knowledge Keepers, and leaders can guide to develop Indigenous-led databases. Sustainability 2020, 12, 47 7 of 9 Indigenous Perspectives. For building sustainability in Indigenous communities, Indigenous perspectives are critical. Studies suggested developing Indigenous perspectives on concepts (i.e., energy, energy management, safe drinking water, and health risk) through Indigenous Elders and Knowledge Keepers’ guidelines. Funding. Funding is one of the critical issues for building sustainability in oil spills management. Most communities suffer for lack of funding during and after oil spills. Therefore, studies strongly suggested federal and provincial governments, research agencies, and companies create a special call for Indigenous CBPAR research, interdisciplinary research, actions-based solutions, and maintain a workforce during and after any oil spills. Ongoing pre-oil spills funding is also needed for educating the community. Develop Indigenous-Led Programs. Indigenous-led programs from and within Indigenous communities are significant for building sustainability for Indigenous communities. These programs are to monitor impacts and assessments, and report the pipeline leaks and drinking water outcomes to implement strategies for finding effective solutions in removing barriers and challenges to safe drinking water, Indigenous health, and their environment. Sustainability in energy justice requires responsible energy development in Indigenous communities. This scoping review paper suggests that when energy is developed in Indigenous communities, there is a need to consider Indigenous peoples’ interests regarding the opportunities and impacts of energy development. Our study found that energy development without Indigenous community engagement has been creating not only serious negative impacts on the environment, but also creating significant barriers for Indigenous everyday practices, including impacts on Indigenous water, agricultural land, traditional hunting and gathering practices, and ceremonies. Therefore, in reviewing recent research on Indigenous communities, this study suggests that following the above recommendations are significant for building energy sustainability in Indigenous land. To achieve this, we strive for relationships that are based on transparency, mutual respect and trust. Author Contributions: Methodology, scoping review; software, google and university library search search, validation, R.D. and M.A.H.; content analysis; R.D. and M.A.H., writing; writing—Nov-Dec, R.D. and M.A.H. All authors have read and agreed to the published version of the manuscript. Funding: This project was funded by Banting Post-Doctoral Fellowship 2018–2020, Canada, grant number RN340033-393630. Conflicts of Interest: The authors declare no conflict of interest. References 1. McGregor, D. The Earth Keepers Solid Waste Management Planning Program: A Collaborative Approach to Utilizing Aboriginal Traditional Knowledge and Western Science in Ontario. Int. J. Can. Stud. 2010, 41, 69. [CrossRef] 2. World Commission on Environment and Development. Our Common Future; Oxford University Press: Oxford, UK, 1987; p. 454. 3. Hurlbert, M.; Rayner, J. Reconciling power, relations, and processes: The role of recognition in the achievement of energy justice for Aboriginal people. Appl. Energy 2018, 228, 1320–1327. [CrossRef] 4. Arksey, H.; O’Malley, L. Scoping studies: Towards a Methodological Framework. Int. J. Soc. Res. Methodol. 2005, 8, 19–32. [CrossRef] 5. Austen, I. In Canada, 2 Provinces Feud Over Pipeline: Will It Bring Jobs or Spills? Available online: https://www.nytimes.com/2018/04/14/world/canada/justin-trudeau-alberta-british-columbia-kinder- morgan-pipeline.html?em_pos=small&emc=edit_cnda_20180421&nl=canada-today&nl_art=1&nlid= 60013975c%3Dedit_cnda_20180421&ref=headline&te=1 (accessed on 23 April 2018). 6. Hayward, J. BC NDP to Argue Trans Mountain Pipeline Expansion not in National Interest. Available online: https://www.theglobeandmail.com/news/british-columbia/bc-ndp-to-argue-trans- mountain-pipeline-expansion-not-in-national-interest/article36446499/ (accessed on 5 January 2019). http://dx.doi.org/10.7202/044163ar http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.apenergy.2018.06.054 http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/1364557032000119616 https://www.nytimes.com/2018/04/14/world/canada/justin-trudeau-alberta-british-columbia-kinder-morgan-pipeline.html?em_pos=small&emc=edit_cnda_20180421&nl=canada-today&nl_art=1&nlid=60013975c%3Dedit_cnda_20180421&ref=headline&te=1 https://www.nytimes.com/2018/04/14/world/canada/justin-trudeau-alberta-british-columbia-kinder-morgan-pipeline.html?em_pos=small&emc=edit_cnda_20180421&nl=canada-today&nl_art=1&nlid=60013975c%3Dedit_cnda_20180421&ref=headline&te=1 https://www.nytimes.com/2018/04/14/world/canada/justin-trudeau-alberta-british-columbia-kinder-morgan-pipeline.html?em_pos=small&emc=edit_cnda_20180421&nl=canada-today&nl_art=1&nlid=60013975c%3Dedit_cnda_20180421&ref=headline&te=1 https://www.theglobeandmail.com/news/british-columbia/bc-ndp-to-argue-trans-mountain-pipeline-expansion-not-in-national-interest/article36446499/ https://www.theglobeandmail.com/news/british-columbia/bc-ndp-to-argue-trans-mountain-pipeline-expansion-not-in-national-interest/article36446499/ Sustainability 2020, 12, 47 8 of 9 7. Raso, K.; Neubauer, R.J. Managing Dissent: Energy Pipelines and “New Right” Politics in Canada. Available online: https://cjc-online.ca/index.php/journal/article/view/2777 (accessed on 21 January 2019). 8. Olive, A. Oil development in the grasslands: Saskatchewan’s Bakken formation and species at risk protection. Cogent Environ. Sci. 2018, 4, 1443666. [CrossRef] 9. Austen, I. Oil Sand Industry in Canada Tied to Higher Carcinogen Level. Available online: https://www.nytimes.com/2013/01/13/world/americas/oil-sand-industry-in-canada-tied-to-higher- carcinogen-level.html (accessed on 4 January 2019). 10. Wilke, R.A.; Freeman, J.W. Potential Health Implications Related to Fracking. JAMA 2017, 318, 1645–1646. [CrossRef] [PubMed] 11. McKay, P. Out of the LOOP: The Fatal Flaw of Alberta’s Oil Export Expansion. Available online: https: //theenergymix.com/2018/03/05/exclusive-out-of-the-loop-the-fatal-flaw-of-albertas-oil-export-expansion/ (accessed on 10 January 2019). 12. Nikiforuk, A. The Arctic Is Not A Casino: The Beaufort Sea Project and the Enduring Hazards of Arctic Offshore Drilling, Greenpeace Canada. 2018. Available online: http://www.restco.ca/BSP_Reprints.shtml (accessed on 23 January 2019). 13. Sinha, S. Energy East pipeline. Extr. Ind. Soc. 2016, 3, 517–552. 14. Atlin, C.; Gibson, R. Lasting regional gains from non-renewable resource extraction: The role of sustainability-based cumulative effects assessment and regional planning for mining development in Canada. Extr. Ind. Soc. 2017, 4, 36–52. [CrossRef] 15. Alava, J.J.; Calle, N. Pipelines imperil Canada’s ecosystem. Science 2017, 355, 6321. [CrossRef] [PubMed] 16. Canadian Press. Plains Midstream Reports Second Oil Spill in Alberta. Available online: http: //business.financialpost.com/2012/06/08/pipeline-company-reports-oil-spill-near-red-deer-river (accessed on 11 February 2019). 17. Canadian Press. Enbridge Elk Point Spill Pumps about 230,000 Litres of Heavy Crude in Alberta. Available online: http://www.huffingtonpost.ca/2012/06/19/enbridge-elk-point-spill-_n_1610613.html (accessed on 23 January 2019). 18. Swift, A.; Swift, L.; Casey-Lefkowitz, S.; Terhune, K.; Droitsch, D. Pipeline and Tanker Trouble: The Impact to British Columbia’s Communities, Rivers and Pacific Coastline from Tar Sands Oil Transport; The National Resource Defense Council: New York, NY, USA, 2011. 19. Government of Canada. Drinking Water Advisories: First Nations South of 60. Available online: https: //www.sac-isc.gc.ca/eng/1506514143353/1533317130660 (accessed on 6 August 2019). 20. Canadian Broadcasting Corporation (CBC). 200 K L of Oil from Husky Energy Pipe Leaked into North Saskatchewan River, Company Says. Available online: http://www.cbc.ca/news/canada/saskatoon/ saskatchewan-government-husky-energypipeline-leaks-oil-1.3690178 (accessed on 23 February 2019). 21. Canadian Broadcasting Corporation (CBC). This River Has Taken a Beating: James Smith Cree Nation Has Serious Concerns after Husky Pipeline Spill. Available online: http://www.cbc.ca/news/canada/saskatoon/ james-smith-cree-nation-concerns-husky-oilspill-1.3742966 (accessed on 23 February 2019). 22. Liu, E. Energy East: Where Oil Meets Water; The Council of Canadians: Ottawa, ON, USA, 2014. 23. The Council of Canadian Acting for Social Justice. Safe Water for First Nations. Available online: https: //canadians.org/fn-water (accessed on 23 January 2019). 24. The UBC Report. Oil Spill in Burrard Inlet Could Cost Vancouver up to $1.2 Billion. Available online: https://www.vancouverobserver.com/news/oil-spill-burrard-inlet-could-cost-vancouver- 12-billion-ubc-report (accessed on 23 January 2019). 25. Todd, Z. Fish, Kin and Hope: Tending to Water Violations in amiskwaciwâskahikan and Treaty Six Territory. Afterall J. Art Context Enq. 2017, 43, 102–107. [CrossRef] 26. Booth, A.L.; Skelton, N.W. You spoil everything! Indigenous peoples and the consequences of industrial development in British Columbia. Environ. Dev. Sustain. 2011, 13, 685. [CrossRef] 27. Wingrove, J. Small Oil Leak Discovered in Alberta. Available online: https://www.theglobeandmail.com/ news/national/small-oil-leak-discovered-in-alberta/article4442357/ (accessed on 15 January 2019). 28. Healing, D. Cleanup of Oil Spill in Saskatchewan Cost $107 Million, Husky Energy Says. Available online: http://www.canadianunderwriter.ca/catastrophes/cleanup-oil-spill-saskatchewan-cost-107- millionhusky-energy-says-1004109375/ (accessed on 23 January 2019). 29. Haarstad, H.; Wanvik, T.I. Carbonscapes and beyond: Conceptualizing the instability of oil landscapes. Progress. Hum. Geogr. 2016, 41, 432–450. [CrossRef] https://cjc-online.ca/index.php/journal/article/view/2777 http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/23311843.2018.1443666 https://www.nytimes.com/2013/01/13/world/americas/oil-sand-industry-in-canada-tied-to-higher-carcinogen-level.html https://www.nytimes.com/2013/01/13/world/americas/oil-sand-industry-in-canada-tied-to-higher-carcinogen-level.html http://dx.doi.org/10.1001/jama.2017.14239 http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/29049815 https://theenergymix.com/2018/03/05/exclusive-out-of-the-loop-the-fatal-flaw-of-albertas-oil-export-expansion/ https://theenergymix.com/2018/03/05/exclusive-out-of-the-loop-the-fatal-flaw-of-albertas-oil-export-expansion/ http://www.restco.ca/BSP_Reprints.shtml http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.exis.2017.01.005 http://dx.doi.org/10.1126/science.aam5609 http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/28082553 http://business.financialpost.com/2012/06/08/pipeline-company-reports-oil-spill-near-red-deer-river http://business.financialpost.com/2012/06/08/pipeline-company-reports-oil-spill-near-red-deer-river http://www.huffingtonpost.ca/2012/06/19/enbridge-elk-point-spill-_n_1610613.html https://www.sac-isc.gc.ca/eng/1506514143353/1533317130660 https://www.sac-isc.gc.ca/eng/1506514143353/1533317130660 http://www.cbc.ca/news/canada/saskatoon/saskatchewan-government-husky-energypipeline-leaks-oil-1.3690178 http://www.cbc.ca/news/canada/saskatoon/saskatchewan-government-husky-energypipeline-leaks-oil-1.3690178 http://www.cbc.ca/news/canada/saskatoon/james-smith-cree-nation-concerns-husky-oilspill-1.3742966 http://www.cbc.ca/news/canada/saskatoon/james-smith-cree-nation-concerns-husky-oilspill-1.3742966 https://canadians.org/fn-water https://canadians.org/fn-water https://www.vancouverobserver.com/news/oil-spill-burrard-inlet-could-cost-vancouver-12-billion-ubc-report https://www.vancouverobserver.com/news/oil-spill-burrard-inlet-could-cost-vancouver-12-billion-ubc-report http://dx.doi.org/10.1086/692559 http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10668-011-9284-x https://www.theglobeandmail.com/news/national/small-oil-leak-discovered-in-alberta/article4442357/ https://www.theglobeandmail.com/news/national/small-oil-leak-discovered-in-alberta/article4442357/ http://www.canadianunderwriter.ca/catastrophe s/cleanup-oil-spill-saskatchewan-cost-107-millionhusky-energy-says-1004109375/ http://www.canadianunderwriter.ca/catastrophe s/cleanup-oil-spill-saskatchewan-cost-107-millionhusky-energy-says-1004109375/ http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0309132516648007 Sustainability 2020, 12, 47 9 of 9 30. Finch, D. Can the Great Slave Rise Again? Calgary Herald. Available online: http://www2.canada.com/ calgaryherald/news/story.html?id=8d29dc87-d191-49f4-8d04-4fb6ba51e797 (accessed on 12 March 2019). 31. Saskatchewan Government. Husky Oil Spill Activity and Response. 2016. Available online: https://www.saskatchewan.ca/government/husky-oil-spill-activity-and-response#status-report (accessed on 12 March 2019). 32. Alberta Energy Regulator (ARG). Nexen Long Lake Pipeline Failure. 2016. Available online: https: //www.aer.ca/compliance-andenforcement/nexen-long-lake (accessed on 12 March 2019). 33. NUKA. Oil Spill Response Analysis; NUKA Research and Planning Group: Vancouver, BC, Canada, 2015. 34. Huseman, J.; Short, D. A slow industrial genocide: Tar sands and the indigenous peoples of northern Alberta. Int. J. Hum. Rights 2012, 16, 216–237. [CrossRef] 35. Jump up. National Energy Board Responding to Pipeline Incident in Central Alberta—Canada News Centre. Available online: https://www.canada.ca/en/news/archive/2015/05/national-energy-board- responding-pipeline-incident-central-alberta.html (accessed on 5 March 2019). 36. Karpouzoglou, T.; Dewulf, A.; Clark, J. Advancing adaptive governance of social-ecological systems through theoretical multiplicity. Environ. Sci. Policy 2016, 57, 1–9. [CrossRef] 37. Lee, K.; Boufadel, M.; Chen, B.; Foght, J.; Hodson, P.; Swanson, S.; Venosa, A. The Behaviour and Environmental Impacts of Crude Oil Released into Aqueous Environments. Available online: https: //rsc-src.ca/sites/default/files/pdf/OIW%20Report_1.pdf (accessed on 12 March 2019). 38. Graham, J. New Rules for Saskatchewan Pipelines after Husky Oil Spill into River. Available online: https://www.ctvnews.ca/business/new-rules-for-saskatchewan-pipelines-after-husky- oil-spill-into-river-1.3180843 (accessed on 12 March 2019). 39. Colquhoun, H.L.; Levac, D.; O’Brien, K.K.; Straus, S.; Tricco, A.C.; Perrier, L.; Kastner, M.; Moher, D. Scoping reviews: Time for clarity in definition, methods, and reporting. J. Clin. Epidemiol. 2014, 67, 1291–1294. [CrossRef] [PubMed] 40. Conklin Métis Local. Stories from a Long Time Ago; Conklin Métis Local #193: Conklin, AB, Canada, 2016. 41. Eaton, E. Climate Politics in the Patch Engaging Saskatchewan’s Oil-Producing Communities on Climate Change Issues. Available online: https://www.policyalternatives.ca/sites/default/files/uploads/publications/ Saskatchewan%20Office/2017/10/ccpa-sk_climate-politics-in-patch_oct2017.pdf (accessed on 12 March 2019). 42. Gardner, T.U.S. Agency Launches Probe after Enbridge Oil Spill. Available online: https: //www.theglobeandmail.com/report-on-business/industry-news/energy-and-resources/us-agency- launches-probe-after-enbridge-oil-spill/article4446882/ (accessed on 15 March 2019). 43. Hoover, E. The River Is in US: Fighting Toxics in a Mohawk Community; University of Minnesota Press: Minneapolis, MN, USA, 2017. 44. Kelly, E.N.; Schindler, D.W.; Hodson, P.V.; Short, J.W.; Radmanovich, R.; Nielsen, C.C. Oil sands development contributes elements toxic at low concentrations to the Athabasca River and its tributaries. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. USA 2010, 107, 16178–16183. [CrossRef] [PubMed] 45. Kuptana, R. Indigenous Peoples in Canada: Politics, Policy and Human Rightsbased Approaches to Development and Relationship-Building. Available online: https://www.facebook.com/notes/ 10152653528630909/ (accessed on 8 August 2018). 46. Tsleil-Waututh Nation. Environmental Assessment Report. Available online: https://twnsacredtrust.ca/ assessment-report-download/ (accessed on 1 May 2019). 47. Nosek, G. Re-imagining Indigenous Peoples’ Role in Natural Resource Development Decision Making: Implementing Free, Prior and Informed Consent in Canada through Indigenous Legal Traditions. Univ. Br. Columbia Law Rev. 2017, 50, 95–160. 48. Morton, B. Kinder Morgan Pipeline Project Faces Hurdles as Crude Oil Price Drops. Available online: http://www.timescolonist.com/news/b-c/kinder-morgan-pipeline-project-faces-hurdles-as- crude-oil-price-drops-1.2022622 (accessed on 6 August 2015). © 2019 by the authors. Licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY) license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/). http://www2.canada.com/calgaryherald/news/story.html?id=8d29dc87-d191-49f4-8d04-4fb6ba51e797 http://www2.canada.com/calgaryherald/news/story.html?id=8d29dc87-d191-49f4-8d04-4fb6ba51e797 https://www.saskatchewan.ca/government/husky-oil-spill-activity-and-response#status-report https://www.aer.ca/compliance-andenforcement/nexen-long-lake https://www.aer.ca/compliance-andenforcement/nexen-long-lake http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/13642987.2011.649593 https://www.canada.ca/en/news/archive/2015/05/national-energy-board-responding-pipeline-incident-central-alberta.html https://www.canada.ca/en/news/archive/2015/05/national-energy-board-responding-pipeline-incident-central-alberta.html http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.envsci.2015.11.011 https://rsc-src.ca/sites/default/files/pdf/OIW%20Report_1.pdf https://rsc-src.ca/sites/default/files/pdf/OIW%20Report_1.pdf https://www.ctvnews.ca/business/new-rules-for-saskatchewan-pipelines-after-husky-oil-spill-into-river-1.3180843 https://www.ctvnews.ca/business/new-rules-for-saskatchewan-pipelines-after-husky-oil-spill-into-river-1.3180843 http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.jclinepi.2014.03.013 http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/25034198 https://www.policyalternatives.ca/sites/default/files/uploads/publications/Saskatchewan%20Office/2017/10/ccpa-sk_climate-politics-in-patch_oct2017.pdf https://www.policyalternatives.ca/sites/default/files/uploads/publications/Saskatchewan%20Office/2017/10/ccpa-sk_climate-politics-in-patch_oct2017.pdf https://www.theglobeandmail.com/report-on-business/industry-news/energy-and-resources/us-agency-launches-probe-after-enbridge-oil-spill/article4446882/ https://www.theglobeandmail.com/report-on-business/industry-news/energy-and-resources/us-agency-launches-probe-after-enbridge-oil-spill/article4446882/ https://www.theglobeandmail.com/report-on-business/industry-news/energy-and-resources/us-agency-launches-probe-after-enbridge-oil-spill/article4446882/ http://dx.doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1008754107 http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/20805486 https://www.facebook.com/notes/10152653528630909/ https://www.facebook.com/notes/10152653528630909/ https://twnsacredtrust.ca/assessment-report-download/ https://twnsacredtrust.ca/assessment-report-download/ http://www.timescolonist.com/news/b-c/kinder-morgan-pipeline-project-faces-hurdles-as-crude-oil-price-drops-1.2022622 http://www.timescolonist.com/news/b-c/kinder-morgan-pipeline-project-faces-hurdles-as-crude-oil-price-drops-1.2022622 http://creativecommons.org/ http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/. Introduction Scoping Methodological Framework of Study Overview Findings from Selected Studies Thematic Analysis from Study Findings Lack of Indigenous Engagement in Energy Management and Pipelines Impact of Pipelines on Indigenous Drinking Water Quality Pipeline Spills/Leaks and Impacts Discussion and Recommendations References work_65et3y44tvgtbfilsbbc2txksu ---- No Job Name BALANCING JUSTICE AND MERCY Reflections on Forgiveness in Judaism Louis E. Newman ABSTRACT The concept of forgiveness is analyzed as a moral gesture toward the offender designed to help restore that individual’s moral standing. Jewish sources on the conditions under which forgiveness is obligatory are explored and two contrasting positions are presented: one in which the obligation to forgive is conditional on the repentance of the offender and another in which people are required to forgive unconditionally. These two positions are shown to represent different ways of framing the offending behavior that rest, in turn, on different ways of balancing the need for justice and for mercy respectively. In the final analysis, Judaism’s two contrasting attitudes toward forgiveness are rooted in different theological assumptions and different ways of construing the very goals of the moral life. The author points out the merits and shortcomings of both positions and concludes with the suggestion that the two complement each other in important ways. KEY WORDS: forgiveness, justice, mercy, Jewish theology, social order Faithfulness and truth meet; justice and well-being kiss. – Psalm 85:11 1. Conceptualizing Forgiveness Forgiveness may be among the most complex and contested topics in moral philosophy and theology. For one thing the very definition of forgiveness is a matter of dispute. Some treat it in a quasi-legal manner as a matter of forgoing retribution, or waiving one’s right to press charges against the offender (Murphy 2003, 15). Others define forgiveness in terms of the inner emotional or psychological state of the one who offers it, as a letting go of resentment toward one’s offender (Grovier 2002). Still others analyze it as a verbal gesture, an example of what John Austin called “performative speech” (Haber 1991). The purpose of forgiveness is similarly contested. It may be designed to effect reconciliation with the offender on a personal level, or to welcome that person back into society. But others see forgiveness primarily as a way of healing the offended Louis E. Newman is the John M. and Elizabeth W. Musser Professor of Religious Studies and Associate Dean of the College and Director of Advising, Carleton College. Louis E. Newman, Carleton College, 1 N. College St., Northfield, MN 55057, lnewman@carleton.edu. JRE 41.3:435–456. © 2013 Journal of Religious Ethics, Inc. party’s own pain, and so imagine that one could forgive the offender without ever telling that person about it.1 This last position is reflected in much contemporary self-help literature and captures an increas- ingly popular view according to which forgiveness is a gift to the one who forgives, essentially an act of self-care (Luskin 2002; Borris- Dunchunstang 2007; and Friedman 2009). Forgiveness is further complicated by the enormous range of circum- stances in which it arises, from the most trivial of missteps (I forgive my friend for not inviting me to his birthday party) to the most heinous of crimes (as when one forgives one’s rapist or the murderer of one’s child). It arises not only in the context of interpersonal relationships, but in relationships between groups and in the sphere of international politics. Forgiveness varies considerably in situations where the offending and offended parties know one another, or even more, when they have a longstanding, intimate relationship, as distinct from situations in which the offender has no prior relationship to the one he hurt. Finally, any cogent understanding of forgiveness must encompass those situations in which one forgives someone who has died, or someone who is entirely anonymous, as well as the special case of self-forgiveness. Even this brief overview suffices to illustrate the many ways in which the notion of forgiveness confounds our efforts to pin it down in any conceptually neat way. I suspect that many of the disputes about forgive- ness in the ever-growing literature on the subject can be traced to the fact that the authors are talking about quite different things, but using the same terminology to describe them.2 It follows that anyone who dares to step into this conceptual quagmire at a minimum owes his reader some working definition of forgiveness. First, it seems clear to me that forgiveness as a moral gesture is other-regarding. Whatever its ultimate purpose—and it is my view that forgiving can be done for a number of quite different reasons—it only counts as a moral act of forgiveness if it is meant to benefit the offender in some way.3 If I “forgive” my abusive father only because I want to placate him and ensure that I receive my share of his estate, I am acting 1 Kolnai 1973, 95 argues that the reconciliation entailed in acts of forgiveness must be mutual, that is, accepted by the offender. But I can see no reason for restricting forgiveness in this way. Certainly we all know of instances in which someone forgives a person who is anonymous (the driver who treated one rudely) or someone who is dead or otherwise unreachable. 2 For an extensive bibliography on forgiveness, see Enright and North 1998, 165–86. 3 This need not preclude the case of forgiving the dead. We often do things on behalf of those who are deceased, as when we fulfill a promise that they made, but were not able to fulfill in their lifetimes. Similarly, we sometimes do things that can honor those who have died, as when we grant posthumous awards, or bring things to light that clear the deceased’s wrongfully besmirched reputation. 436 Journal of Religious Ethics out of self-interest, not to relieve him of guilt or to demonstrate that my love is stronger than his misdeed, or out of any (re)consideration of his moral standing at all (Couenhoven 2010). Similarly, the idea that forgive- ness is primarily a gift to oneself confuses the purpose of forgiveness with its secondary effects. There is no doubt that in many cases there are often powerful emotional benefits for one who forgives. But if forgiveness is to have any moral meaning, it must be done primarily as a response to and for the benefit of the offender. The person who “forgives” another in order to feel better is akin to the person who gives a large gift to charity, not because she cares at all about the charity, but simply to avoid the burden of a major tax liability. So we should be clear at the outset that some acts that appear to be forgiveness in the moral sense are really nothing of the sort. And it is only forgiveness as a moral gesture that interests me here. Second, forgiveness encompasses both emotional and behavioral ele- ments. One who claims to forgive and even renews a relationship with his offender, but who inwardly continues to perseverate over the offense, to nurse resentments and ill will, has not genuinely forgiven the offender. Conversely, one who has emotionally let go of those hard feelings, but who refuses to treat the offender as a person whose moral standing has been at least partially, if not wholly, restored, has undergone a change of heart, but not really accepted the offender as forgiven. So at least ideally forgiveness will manifest itself both as a change of attitude and a change in behavior toward one’s offender.4 Third, I think forgiveness admits of gradations; it is not an all-or- nothing proposition. For this reason it is a mistake to tie forgiveness too closely to reconciliation. At one end of the spectrum it is certainly the case that forgiveness can yield a new and deeper relationship between two people who have been estranged, as when a marriage is made stronger after one partner comes to forgive the other for an act of betrayal. But there are less dramatic cases in which forgiveness merely brings a broken relationship back to neutral ground, as it were. Here there is no deep reconciliation, only a cessation of hostility and a commitment to treat the other respectfully, despite past transgressions. Forgiveness, then, does not require that the two parties involved arrive at any particular harmonious 4 I recognize that this claim is controversial and that some will want to count as forgiveness some gestures that are either entirely emotional or (perhaps less often) entirely behavioral. But there are good reasons for maintaining a model of forgiveness that encom- passes both elements, at least as the paradigm case. After all, moral transgressions affect the injured party emotionally (and often physically) and also change the social (and often legal) standing of the offender. If forgiveness is meant to mitigate the effects of the transgression, then, we should expect that it will do so by addressing both the emotional state of the injured party and the social standing of the offender. In proposing this model of forgiveness I nonetheless recognize that there is a wide range of moral gestures with strong “family resemblances” to this paradigm and that these, too, are worthy of consideration. Balancing Justice and Mercy 437 end-state, only that they move beyond the state of moral disequilibrium that characterizes a relationship broken by harmful or disrespectful acts. With these considerations in mind, then, I will define forgiveness as a moral gesture offered by the offended party to the offending party as a way of restoring that person’s moral standing (whether in the context of their relationship or in some larger, social context), which entails adjusting one’s feelings about and behavior toward that person in ways that minimize (and sometimes entirely negate) the ongoing effects of the person’s past offense.5 The question at hand is how classical Jewish sources view acts of forgiveness so defined.6 In what follows I will argue that there are two primary strands within this tradition that understand the obligation to forgive quite differently. I will then suggest that these differences can be traced to two alternative conceptions of the meaning of forgiveness and its place in the religious life. That is, whether forgiveness is obligatory and, if so, why turns out to depend on different understandings of the way in which this moral gesture is embedded in a web of beliefs about God’s love, the extent of our responsibilities for the behavior of others, and the purpose of our moral behavior in general. 2. Conditional Forgiveness Many Jewish discussions of our topic regard forgiveness as the required response to an offender who has taken appropriate steps to acknowledge his wrongdoing and repair the damage. The source most often cited in support of this view is M. Baba Kamma 8:77: Even though a person gives [monetary compensation] to one [whom he has shamed], he is not forgiven until he asks [explicitly for forgiveness] from him [whom he has shamed]. . . . And whence do we derive the principle that he who is called upon to forgive should not be hard-hearted? It is written [Genesis 20:17], “Then Abraham interceded with God, and God healed Abimelech.” 5 In what follows I will restrict my comments to cases of interpersonal forgiveness, though I think that many of the principles I evoke here could be applied to other spheres of human activity. 6 I will deal here only with cases of interpersonal forgiveness between individuals who have had direct contact with one another. Forgiveness between groups and/or nations for historic injustices raises additional complexities insofar as such cases involve a more symbolic dimension and frequently have their meaning in larger systems of political behavior. 7 Unless otherwise noted, all translations from classical rabbinic literature and Jewish lawcodes are my own. This article uses standard abbreviations: “M.” for the Mishnah, “B.” for the Babylonian Talmud, “T.” for the Tosefta, and “MT” for Moses Maimonides’s Mishneh Torah (c. 1180). 438 Journal of Religious Ethics This early rabbinic ruling underscores a number of important points.8 First, the purpose of forgiveness is essentially restorative. Just as one restores a situation of material equity through the payment of damages, one must likewise restore the state of moral equilibrium that has been disturbed by the offense in question. Such a reconciliation can be accom- plished only by seeking forgiveness directly from the individual harmed. Second, the rabbis generally assume that the primary responsibility for repairing a “moral gap” lies with the person who created it. In the proper course of things, that is, seeking forgiveness precedes granting it. The interrelationship of these two duties—seeking forgiveness and granting it—is expressed with characteristic clarity and precision by Maimonides: Even if one only injured the other in words [and not in deeds], he must pacify him and approach him until he forgives him. If his fellow does not wish to forgive him, the other person brings a line of three of his friends who [in turn] approach the offended person and request from him [that he grant forgiveness]. If he is not accepting of them, he brings a second [cadre of friends] and then a third. If he still does not wish [to grant forgiveness], one leaves him and goes his own way, and the person who would not forgive is himself the sinner. (MT Laws of Repentance, 2:9) 8 Daniel Statman takes issue with the following interpretation of this mishnah, arguing that it is not about acquiring forgiveness from the one wronged at all, but rather from God and that the point of the passage is that Abimelech is in need of Abraham’s prayer to God on his behalf. Statman goes on to reject the view that this source and others cited support the view that Judaism insists on the repentance of the transgressor as a condition of the duty to forgive him. However, classical and modern commentaries to the Mishnah read it as I have, and the structure of the passage seems to require that there is a symmetry between the first clause, in which the offender is required to ask for forgiveness (presumably from the offended party) and the second clause, in which the offended party is told not to withhold forgiveness. Moreover, a number of other passages, both from Maimonides and from Karo, repeatedly emphasize that “if the offender repents and pleads for forgiveness, he should be forgiven.” If the repentance of the offender were not a precondition for this duty to forgive, why would these authorities state the rule in this way, rather than simply state that offended persons must always unilaterally forgive those who offend them? Statman also critiques a position that he mistakenly attributes to me based on his reading of Newman 1987. In that article I argued that, by insisting that forgiveness is obligatory only in cases where the offender has repented, Judaism avoids the problem that forgiveness can be tantamount to condoning the offense. Contra Statman, however, neither in that article nor here do I endorse the view that forgiveness is paradoxical in that if the offender repents, it is superfluous, and if the offender does not repent, it is unwarranted (see Kolnai 1973 for an articulation of this position). Plainly, even in cases where the offender repents, the injured party may have legitimate reasons for continued feelings of resentment, anger, and even the desire for retribution where the offense was extremely serious or irreversible. So forgiveness is not superfluous. I do, however, now agree with the conclusion of Statman’s article that Judaism (at least sometimes) affirms the value of unconditional forgiveness, which is a change from the position I defended in my earlier article. See Statman 2012. Balancing Justice and Mercy 439 Maimonides emphasizes what the Mishnah passage only implied, that the offender bears primary responsibility for initiating the process of forgive- ness. On the other hand, the offended individual has a corresponding duty to forgive anyone who sincerely requests it and the failure to do so constitutes an offense no less than the action of the initial offender. This formulation of the duty to forgive has a long history in Jewish legal sources and finds expression again in the famous sixteenth-century law code of Joseph Karo, the Shulh· an Arukh. One who harms his neighbor, even if he compensates him according to the five things [for damage, for pain, for healing, for loss of time and for shame; see M. Baba Kamma 8:1] he is not forgiven until he requests it [from the one he harmed] and he forgives him. And it is forbidden for the injured one to be hard-hearted about forgiving, for this is not the way of Jews. Rather, once the injurer requests from him and pleads with him once or twice, and it is obvious that he has repented of his sin and regrets his evil ways, he should forgive him. And everyone who hurries to forgive is to be praised, and the spirit of the sages is pleased with him. (Hoshen Mishpat 422, emphasis added) It is interesting that Karo makes explicit the expectation that forgiving quickly is praiseworthy, and I will return below to the question of why these virtues of generosity and compassion are so highly valued. But it is worth noting here that the tendency to forgive is cast as something that “the sages are pleased with,” a classic rabbinic phrase used to indicate something that is morally praiseworthy, but not legally required.9 What I am calling here the legalistic perspective on forgiveness will strike many familiar with the literature of this subject as unduly restric- tive insofar as it portrays the duty to forgive as conditional. Why would we not have a duty to forgive unilaterally? The problem with uncon- ditional forgiveness seems to lie with the notion that it threatens to undermine the moral condemnation of the offender. This emerges again in Maimonides’s formulation of the law in Leviticus 19:17 that we are required to rebuke others for their misdeeds. And thus it is said, “You shall surely rebuke your neighbor” (Leviticus 19:17). If the offender repents and pleads for forgiveness, he should be forgiven. The forgiver should not be obdurate, as it is said, “And Abraham prayed unto God (for Abimelech).” (Genesis 20:17) If one observes that a person committed a sin or walks in a way that is not good, it is a duty to bring the erring man back to the right path and point out to him that he is wronging himself by his evil courses. . . . And so one is bound to continue the admonitions until the sinner assaults the admonisher 9 See my discussion of this and other similar terms in Newman 1998, 46–49. 440 Journal of Religious Ethics and says to him “I refuse to listen.” Whoever is in a position to prevent wrongdoing and does not do so is responsible for the iniquity of all the wrongdoers whom he might have restrained. (MT Laws of Ethical Conduct, 6:6–7)10 Forgiveness granted unconditionally would threaten to undermine or ignore the culpability of the offender. Indeed, it is not difficult to imagine an offender who might come to rely on the assurance of forgiveness and take this as license to continue transgressing.11 So it is only the offender’s repentance that entitles him to forgiveness, for the person has then distanced himself from the harm he caused, disowned it, as it were, and so has a claim on those he harmed to consider him in a new light. Indeed, in some sources the rabbis press this point further, proposing that prior to repentance one even has an obligation to hate the sinner. As Maimonides puts it, “The sages decreed that if one all alone sees another committing a crime and warns him against it and he does not desist, one is obligated to hate him until he repents and leaves his evil ways” (MT Laws of Homicide and Preservation of Life, 13:14).12 This legalistic perspective gives paramount importance to the concerns of justice and to the idea that each member of the community is res- ponsible for the behavior of all others. In this context, unconditional forgiveness is potentially dangerous, for it opens the door to letting the wrongdoer “off the hook,” and so has possibly far-reaching ramifications for the social order. Only when we take responsibility to ensure that transgressors are brought back in line—first by rebuking them and then by withholding our forgiveness until they reform their ways—can we make this society a place in which respect for legal and moral norms is reinforced. And so forgiveness cannot be a duty in cases where the offender has not first acknowledged his offense and taken steps to rectify it. In short, forgiveness on this view takes its place within a system of legal and moral accountability; offering it to those who have not earned it would encourage transgressors, undermine social norms, and abrogate our duty to chastise those who violate the law. 3. Unconditional Forgiveness In light of the foregoing discussion it may come as a surprise that there is a starkly different view in many classical Jewish sources, according to 10 Translation taken from Maimonides 1972, 61. 11 Other passages in rabbinic literature consider just this possibility in connection with the view that the Day of Atonement automatically absolves all sinners of their sins when it states that for “one who sins and says, ‘The Day of Atonement will atone,’ the Day of Atonement does not atone” (M. Avot 8:9). 12 Translation taken from Maimonides 1972, 168–69. See also B. Pesah· im 113b; The Fathers According to Rabbi Nathan 16. Balancing Justice and Mercy 441 which one is required to forgive even those who have not repented. The duty to offer such “unearned” forgiveness is articulated in the following early rabbinic source: “He who injures his fellow, even though the one who did the injury did not seek [forgiveness], from the injured party—the injured party nonetheless has to seek mercy for him, since it says, ‘Then Abraham prayed to God, and God healed Abimelech’ (Gen. 20:17)” (T. Baba Kamma 9:29, emphasis added). The contrast with the preceding could hardly be more stark, especially given that the very same prooftext is offered in support of the view that unconditional forgiveness is a duty, and that the text derives from the same period as the Mishnah text cited above. Indeed, the Talmud records that Mar Zutra, each evening before retiring to bed, made a practice of forgiving all who harmed him, a practice that is reflected in many traditional prayerbooks to this day (B. Megillah 28a). In one formulation of this prayer, the offer of forgiveness is especially expansive: “I hereby forgive and absolve anyone who has angered or provoked me or sinned against me, physically or financially or by failing to give me due respect, or in any other matter relating to me, involuntarily or willingly, inadvertently or deliberately, whether in word or deed: let no one incur punishment because of me” (Sacks 2009, 294). The absence of any mention of repentance on the part of those being forgiven underscores that this act of forgiveness is offered freely as an expression of goodwill. It is also worth noting that the idea is not merely to relinquish feelings of resentment, but also to ask that God be merciful in not punishing the offender. This further highlights the fact that we are dealing here with a theory of forgiveness that places it beyond the concerns of the judicial system that figured so prominently in the texts considered above. For while this text does not explicitly link unconditional forgiveness to forgoing human punishment, it is hard to imagine that the author of this prayer would beseech God to forgo punishment of the offender, but then insist on exacting it in an earthly court. This emphasis on compassion, though it seems to appear predominantly in non-legal sources within the tradition, is reflected as well in certain legal texts. In Exodus 23:4–5 we find that “if you meet your enemy’s ox or his ass going astray, you shall surely bring it back to him again. If you see the ass of him that hates you lying under its burden, and would forbear to unload it, you shall surely unload it with him.” The implication of this rule is that we are not to let feelings of animosity stand in the way of assisting those in need, and while this does not precisely command one to forgive the enemy, it surely commands one to treat the enemy with the same consid- eration due to non-enemies.13 Subsequent rabbinic commentary on this 13 The biblical injunction not to take vengeance or bear a grudge against one’s neighbor (Leviticus 19:18) similarly does not directly require forgiveness, but it does preclude the retributive attitude that underlies the refusal to forgive. 442 Journal of Religious Ethics biblical rule makes explicit the moral purpose of the rule: “[If one has the choice of helping] his friend to load up his ass, or his enemy to unload his ass, his religious duty is to unload the ass with his enemy [Ex. 23:4], so as to break his heart [that is, to break his instinctive desire to ill-treat his enemy]” (T. Baba Metsi’a 2:26).14 Cultivating compassion for those who (presumably) have wronged us, then, is a positive commandment, as well as a traditional, pietistic practice. It is consonant with the view that we are required to forgive others, irrespective of their posture toward us, without first rebuking them or insisting on their repentance. If practiced on a regular basis, such unconditional forgiveness would reinforce a generosity of spirit even—perhaps especially—toward those who have not repented or sought forgiveness. How shall we understand this very different attitude toward forgive- ness in Judaism? What might be the grounds for such a practice of unconditional forgiveness? I believe that there are two separate sets of considerations that find expression in this responsibility to forgive unconditionally. The first is the principle of imitatio Dei, coupled with the view that God’s nature is essentially forgiving. These ideas are found throughout biblical and rab- binic literature,15 so a few characteristic examples will suffice to illustrate the point. The prophetic literature is full of passages depicting God as endlessly merciful. Micah 7:18–19 is typical: Who is a God like You, Forgiving iniquity And passing over transgression; Who has not maintained His wrath forever Against the remnant of His own people, Because He loves graciousness! He will take us back in love; He will cover up our iniquities, You will hurl all our sins Into the depths of the sea. Similarly, the High Holiday liturgy includes the following passage: “God, Sovereign who sits on a throne of mercy, acting with unbounded grace, 14 See also Sifre Deuteronomy 222 and 225, and B. Baba Metsi’a 32b. Maimonides explains the purpose of the rule as “to curb one’s evil inclination”; see MT Laws of Murder and Preservation of Life, 13:13. 15 To be sure, Jewish sources about God’s nature are not so consistent, as I will discuss below. But it is striking that in each instance where the rabbis reflect on the value of following God’s example, they consistently point to God’s infinitely compassionate, loving nature. They famously even pervert the meaning of Exodus 34:6–7, which comes to have a central place in the traditional liturgy on holidays and especially on Rosh Hashanah and Yom Kippur, by dropping those clauses of the verse that reference God’s retribution against those who violate God’s law. Balancing Justice and Mercy 443 forgiving the sins of Your people, one by one, as each comes before You, generously forgiving sinners and pardoning transgressors, acting chari- tably with every living thing: do not repay them for their misdeeds” (Rabbinical Assembly 2010, 261). And when the rabbis elaborate on the meaning of Deuteronomy 28:9, “you shall walk in God’s ways,” they comment: This means, as the ways of Heaven are to be gracious, graciously bestowing gifts not only upon those who know Him but also upon those who do not know Him, so you are to bestow gifts upon one another. And, as the ways of Heaven are to be long-suffering, long-suffering with the wicked and then accepting them in repentance, so you are to be long-suffering [with the wicked] for their good and not impatient to impose punishment upon them. For, as the ways of Heaven are abundant in lovingkindness, ever leaning to lovingkindness, so are you ever to lean toward doing lovingkindness to others rather than lean toward doing them harm. (Tanna Debe Eliyyahu 135; Braude and Kapstein 1981, 333) To be forgiving, then, is nothing less than to reflect and extend God’s own forgiving nature in our relationships with others. In a sense, the under- lying logic is that if God can be counted upon to be this loving toward those who transgress, by what right can we hold transgressors to a higher standard? The rabbis implicitly acknowledge this connection, when they suggest that if we extend forgiveness to others, God will reward us by doing likewise (B. Megillah 28a). In a very clever reading of the verse from Micah cited above, the rabbis argue: “Raba said, ‘Anyone who passes over the traits [of those who injure him]—his own transgressions will be passed over. As it is written (Micah 7:18): ‘forgiving iniquity and passing over transgression.’ For whom does [God] forgive iniquity? For the one who passes over transgressions [committed against him]” (B. Rosh Hashanah 17a). By imitating God’s forgiveness, we also evoke it. The implications of this theology are far-reaching. The world was established by a loving God who accepts and forgives human imper- fections. When we channel this divine quality, we not only draw closer to God, we become agents of God’s compassion and love in the world. In one of the emotional climaxes of the High Holiday liturgy, the congregation sings: “Avinu malkeinu [Our Father, our King], have mercy on us, answer us, for our deeds are insufficient; deal with us charitably and lovingly, and redeem us” (Rabbinical Assembly 2010, 94). From this perspective, we are all morally flawed, all in need of divine forgiveness, all the undeserving beneficiaries of God’s compassion. As a result, we have no moral choice but to extend this same compassion to those who harm us; to do otherwise would demonstrate a stunning lack of gratitude, as well as monumental hypocrisy. A second basis for this obligation to forgive unconditionally may be found in the tradition’s emphasis on personal humility. In the view of 444 Journal of Religious Ethics many it is a virtue to cultivate humility, which includes minimizing one’s achievements, reflecting regularly on one’s mortality, and being especially scrupulous about one’s own behavior, lest one inadvertently become arro- gant or complacent about one’s moral worthiness. In the words of one classical source: “If you have done your fellow a slight wrong, let it be a serious matter in your eyes; but if you have done your fellow much good, let it be a trifle in your eyes. And if your fellow has done you a slight favor, let it be a great thing in your eyes; if your fellow has done you a great evil, let it be a little thing in your eyes” (The Fathers According to Rabbi Nathan, 41:11; see also Derekh Eretz Zutta 1:3). The implication of this is that one should “judge everyone favorably [lit. ‘on the side of their merits’]” (M. Avot 1:6). Cultivating such an attitude toward oneself and others would lead inevitably to an inclination toward forgiveness. To withhold forgiveness is to continue to assert one’s moral superiority over the offender. It is to say, in effect, “as the injured party, I have a moral claim against you, and I will exercise that claim against you until you convince me that you have disavowed your immoral behavior.” While this may be morally justifiable—after all, the offender does owe a kind of moral debt to the one he harmed, and the latter is entitled to “collect”—this attitude is not consonant with the sort of humility that the rabbis often encourage. In this way, unconditional forgiveness is grounded in a different way of construing the relationship between the offended and the offender. Rather than highlighting the moral distance between them, the tradition encour- ages people to practice a kind of humility that continually prompts us to minimize that moral gap, or even to close it entirely.16 Whatever the offense committed against us, we are essentially no better, no more moral, than those who committed it. From this perspective, we do well to forgive others, whether they have “earned” it or not. For the question here is not whether the offender deserves our forgiveness, but whether we deserve to see ourselves as more worthy than they. Forgiveness is nothing less than the expression of an attitude that we are all more or less equally flawed, hence we had best refrain from exerting our moral superiority over others. 4. Reframing Forgiveness How are we to make sense of these starkly contrasting views of forgiveness in Judaism? It is important here that we avoid the path of least resistance, which is always to portray our religious traditions as 16 Roberts 1995 captures one aspect of this attitude, which he terms “forgivingness,” when he notes that it is essentially a disinclination on the part of the injured party to remain in a state of alienation from the offender, either this particular offender or all offenders in general (294). Balancing Justice and Mercy 445 more homogeneous than they actually are and, in the process, to explain away those elements that are not to one’s liking. If one surveys the literature of Jewish views of forgiveness, it seems that this tendency is much in evidence. Most authorities will contend that the legal view presented above is dominant and often contrast this view with the supposedly dominant Christian view, according to which we are obligated to forgive everyone all the time, and as quickly as possible. So, even as sophisticated a thinker as Elliot Dorff, for whom I have the highest regard, writes, “if the offender never admits wrongdoing, then even if he or she has served a prison term, the very first step in return has not been achieved and no forgiveness can legitimately be demanded of the victims.” Then, after acknowledging that Judaism values compassion and mercy as well as justice, he concludes, although gross offenses should probably not be forgiven without sincere attempts to engage in the process of return, one might be prone to forgive more minor offenses without such a process, both as a pragmatic way of getting on with one’s life and possibly of restoring a friendship and also as an expression of the religious demand that we imitate God. Such free forgiveness, though, becomes harder to justify as the offense grows larger. . . . Then God’s righteousness seems to be the divine attribute that we should emulate. (Dorff 2003, 222–24) While Dorff tries valiantly to accommodate both of the views noted above, he clearly sees one as dominant and can, at best, find room for the idea of unconditional forgiveness only when the offenses involved are relatively minor.17 But suppose that, instead of arbitrarily asserting the dominance of one view over the other, we give each its due. The question we then face is: what sets of assumptions within the tradition make it possible for two such different views of forgiveness to emerge? One way to make sense of these divergent views would be to explain them in terms of alternative moral theories. We might posit, then, that the legal view accords with a social ethic concerned primarily with the maintenance of social order. Accordingly, it makes the duty to forgive dependent on the prior trans- formation of the offender. By contrast, the view that forgiveness should be 17 So, too, Telushkin 2006 in which he acknowledges that Judaism expects people to be forgiving, but summarizes the tradition’s view that “Generally, forgiveness should be dependent on the offending party’s repentance” (1:196). Another version of the same position is articulated by Schimmel 2002 where he writes in reference to Jewish views of forgiveness, “We have to imitate God, and God, for the most part, punishes unrepentant sinners and forgives repentant ones. . . . Some of the differences between rabbinic Judaism and Chris- tianity are ones of emphasis rather than of the absolute presence or absence of a particular concept or value. Repentance and justice are values in Christianity, just as forgiveness is a value in rabbinic Judaism. But the former are emphasized more in rabbinic Judaism and the latter in certain Christian denominations” (69). 446 Journal of Religious Ethics unconditional could be associated with a virtue ethic that is concerned primarily with the cultivation of personal humility and godliness. The moral gesture of forgiveness, then, might be viewed in terms of the moral character of the one who forgives. We might be tempted to conclude, then, that forgiveness is either a matter of (circumscribed) legal duty or of (unconditional) personal virtue. But such a sharp distinction does not do justice to our sources. After all, even some of the legal sources recognize and praise the virtue of forgiving quickly and one of the legal sources requires unconditional forgiveness. Conversely, those who expound the virtue of unconditional forgiveness certainly also believe that it is a duty to rebuke transgressors, as the Torah commands. So our sources do not permit us to posit a dichotomy between a social ethic that emphasizes justice and hence conditional forgiveness and a virtue ethic that emphasizes mercy and hence uncon- ditional forgiveness. If we wish to understand the roots of these two contrasting perspectives on forgiveness, we will do well to examine more carefully just what the moral gesture of forgiveness entails. That is, we will need to explore what understanding of forgiveness—its purpose and meaning—underlies these two contrasting views, and how each of them represents an authentically Jewish view. To answer that question, we do well to refer to the work of Robert Enright and Joanna North. As North describes it, the essence of forgive- ness entails a “reframing” of the offender “whereby the wrongdoer can be regarded as someone over and above the wrong he has committed, a means of ‘separating’ the wrongdoer from the wrong he has done. This is the most crucial stage in the whole process of forgiveness” (North 1998, 24).18 North goes on to explain that this process of reframing enables the victim to see the wrongdoer as a whole person and to contextualize the wrongful deed as something that occurred in particular circumstances, for particular reasons. The wrongdoer cannot, then, be reduced to this particular hurtful action.19 This analysis of forgiveness has the dual virtue of both providing some conceptual clarity about the nature of forgiveness and capturing what 18 Of course, this view parallels the teaching frequently attributed to Jesus, but not actually articulated in any single biblical verse, that we should “hate the sin, but love the sinner.” 19 Hampton 1988 expresses this view of forgiveness with particular clarity. “Forgiveness is thus the decision to see a wrongdoer in a new, more favorable light. Nor is this decision in any way a condonation of wrong. The forgiver never gives us her opposition to the wrongdoer’s action, nor does she even give up her opposition to the wrongdoer’s bad character traits. Instead, she revises her judgment of the person himself—where that person is understood to be something other than or more than the character traits of which she does not approve. And she reaches the honest decision that this person does not merit her moral hatred, because he is still decent despite his action” (84–85). Balancing Justice and Mercy 447 many dozens of subjects in psychological studies of forgiveness say about their own experiences of forgiving (Enright, Freedman, and Rique 1998). But this notion of “reframing” the offender also opens the door to a more extended analysis of the process and purpose of this sort of moral gesture. In fact, I think the contrasting Jewish perspectives on forgiveness noted above enable us to see that this act of reframing is more complex and variable than we might at first imagine. Accordingly, I now want to extend North’s analysis by suggesting that Jewish views of forgiveness need to be interpreted in terms of the ways in which and the reasons for which the offender’s past misdeeds are “reframed.” One kind of reframing focuses very narrowly on the particular misdeed of a particular individual offender. This act demands a response, and the sort of response that seems warranted might just depend on whether we think it is typical or atypical of this individual, whether it is characteristic or an aberration. The only way we can know this is if we focus on this individual’s life, and especially on whether the offender takes action to disavow the harmful behavior and replace it with positive behaviors. That is, our assessment of the misdeed depends on whether the offender seems willing to redress the wrong and, as the tradition says, “return in repentance.” Framed in this way, our forgiveness of any particular misdeed will depend on how it fits within a larger narrative of the offender’s life, especially how his or her life unfolds after the transgression in question. So it is that some Jewish authorities insist that there is no (required) forgiveness without prior repentance. But we might reframe the hurtful deed in a somewhat broader context, that is, in the context of the offender’s life in society. Here the focus shifts from the life story of the offender to the place of the offender in relation to others who have not been party to this particular offense. This is where the concern for rebuking transgressors and hating the sinner comes in. For if we attend to the potential harm that might be caused to other innocent people in the future if this offender’s behavior is not redressed, then we will see this deed very differently. Our response will be condi- tioned by a concern to protect society and reinforce its norms. Now the proper response to this offender will be considered not as a matter of restoring a relationship between these two individuals in isolation, but rather as a matter of restoring a network of social relationships, present and future, that has been frayed by this offense. Framed in this way, our forgiveness will depend on the way in which we assess the ramifications of this offense for the community at large. We may widen our framing of the offense still more, by focusing not on this offense alone, but on all offenses by all of us, not only here and now, but in general. Now this particular offender’s action will be viewed as emblematic of the human propensity to hurtful behavior overall. Our concern is no longer with the particulars of this offender’s life or even 448 Journal of Religious Ethics the potential that he or she will offend against others in the future. Rather, we choose to see the misdeed as just one instance among count- less others that all of us have done or will do, precisely because all of us are flawed creatures. And insofar as we look past the details of this transgression, we will respond to the offender as one flawed person to another and, in Jesus’ words, “let the one who has not sinned cast the first stone” (John 8:7). This way of reframing the offender’s behavior is grounded in the attitude of humility I discussed above, for now I see this offense as part and parcel of human fallibility broadly construed. Framed in this way, our forgiveness will depend on the extent to which we affirm the common human failings that offender and offended alike are subject to. Finally, we might widen our focus yet more to encompass our relation- ship with God. Insofar as we hold certain beliefs about God’s goodness and justice, as well as a desire to do God’s will or strive to emulate God’s qualities, we will see ourselves and the offender in an entirely different light. Our responses to everyone—not only offenders and certainly not only the particular individual who offended against us on this occasion— will be conditioned by a vision of the world as we imagine God would want it. In this situation the goal of imitating God will motivate us to make ourselves conduits for God’s action in the world, which almost certainly will entail emphasizing some ideals for our conduct that may be more aspirational than pragmatic. Framed in this way, our forgiveness will depend on placing our interaction with this particular offender in the context of our relationship with God and our desire to reshape the world in God’s image. Each of these four “reframings” focuses us on different aspects of the same situation by placing it in ever-broader contexts. It is much like a lens that can be adjusted from telephoto to wide-angle, and so can take in the same scene by focusing on everything from a single petal of a single flower up to the entire landscape of which this flower is but the tiniest part. No one of these shots is “truer” than any other; all capture accurately what the shutter lets in. And the same is true, I think, for the ways in which we frame any offender’s behavior. We think about the problem of forgive- ness differently depending on the way we frame the situation in which it arises. But to note this broad range of possibilities within Jewish tradition is not, of course, to suggest that the choice among them is arbitrary or inconsequential. Quite the contrary. How we choose to frame the offender’s behavior is of the utmost consequence, and not only because it will determine in large part our immediate response—whether we demand that the moral debt be “repaid” or whether we “pass over the transgres- sion.” For as we have seen, the choice to forgive or not is correlated with our attitudes to justice and mercy. In the final analysis, I think, it turns Balancing Justice and Mercy 449 on the question of how we think about the very nature and purpose of the moral life. It is to these questions that I wish to turn now in the final section of this paper. 5. Justice and Mercy: Reconsidering the Place of Forgiveness in Judaism Let me return for a moment to the definition of forgiveness I offered at the outset of this discussion. I suggested that forgiveness is a moral gesture offered by the offended party to the offending party as a way of restoring that person’s moral standing, which entails adjusting one’s feelings about and behavior toward that person in ways that minimize (and sometimes entirely negate) the ongoing effects of the person’s past offense. We have now seen that Judaism endorses two fundamentally different ways of thinking about when forgiveness is called for, and that behind these alternative views lie a host of other beliefs and values about the offender, the social order, our susceptibility to moral mistakes, and our relationship to God, among others. Depending on how we frame the offender’s behavior, one or more of these considerations will come into play. Judaism can accommodate more than one way of understanding forgiveness because it makes room for more than one way of framing our response to the offender’s behavior. But it is worth highlighting that both views of forgiveness have at least this much in common: both constitute responses to the transgres- sion, both involve “restoring the moral standing of the offender.” From the perspective of those who view the obligation to forgive as conditional, the offender must first engage in repentance as a condition of his or her rehabilitation. The primary work of restoring one’s moral standing, then, lies with the offender; once he or she has repented, we restore their moral standing, saying in effect, “we relinquish our condemnation of you for your past behavior in consideration of your subsequent (repentant) behavior.” By contrast, unconditional forgiveness meets the offender more than halfway. It represents an offer to restore the moral standing of the offender as a gift, whether as a show of solidarity (“we are all morally broken”) or as an effort to emulate God’s boundless love (“I will treat you compassionately just as God treats all of us compassionately”). By responding to the offender’s moral failure with an excess of moral generosity, this act of forgiveness invites the offender into a different moral realm. It communicates a powerful message to the offender: “Your moral failings notwithstanding, we affirm your moral worth. We will negate the ongoing effects of your past behavior for you, thereby giving you a clean slate and a chance to begin anew.” The key point is that both types of forgiveness transform offenders, the first by “holding their feet to the fire,” so to speak, and the second by lifting them out of the moral 450 Journal of Religious Ethics pit into which they have fallen when they cannot (or will not) climb out on their own power.20 This way of thinking about unconditional forgiveness is powerfully captured in a famous teaching of the Hasidic rabbi, Nahman of Bratslav, who wrote, “Know that you must judge everyone with an eye to their merits. Even regarding those who are completely wicked, one must search and find some small way in which they are not wicked and with respect to this bit of goodness, judge them with an eye to their merits. In this way, one truly elevates their merit and thereby encourages them to repent” (Likutei Moharan, 282). The power of unconditional forgiveness is pre- cisely that the recipient of this gift may come to see him or herself in a new light. Having been restored to their prior moral standing unilaterally, they may be motivated to do the work of turning their lives around, whether out of a sense of gratitude or simply because a way forward has been opened for them.21 This way of explaining the difference between the two Jewish views of forgiveness returns us to what I think is really at the root of this dispute, namely, the relationship between justice and mercy. On the view of forgiveness as conditional, justice is primary. Offenders must be made to pay their moral debts, both because the offended party is entitled to some “compensation,” and because the social order depends on condemn- ing moral transgressions. On the view of forgiveness as unconditional, mercy is primary. Since our duty is always to channel God’s goodness and bring it more fully into the world, we have no choice but to reach out to the offender with compassion. The focus here is not on what the offender has earned, but rather on what all of us need in order to survive in a world where we inevitably both hurt others and are hurt by them.22 20 I recognize that this might not be the intention in every case where unconditional forgiveness is practiced, but I suggest that it is the effect of doing so, at least insofar as the offender is made aware that he or she has been forgiven. 21 Of course, it is possible that the one who is forgiven will not respond in this way at all, but rather act as though they have been given a “get out of jail free” card and continue in their immoral ways. This is precisely the risk inherent in unconditional forgiveness. Murphy and Hampton 1988 regards forgiveness offered as a way to induce the repentance of the offender as “arrogant” (30). But, if so, then so too is the teacher who provides undeserved words of encouragement to a struggling student who might be motivated to try harder as a result. Indeed, offering forgiveness as an act of generosity in this way is precisely to use one’s own behavior as a moral model for the offender, calling forth the angels of her better self. Nonetheless, Kolnai 1973 is certainly right that this is not a necessary dimension of forgiveness. “It is possible to ‘re-accept’ somebody—the essence of forgiveness—without exculpating him and without hoping for anything like a thoroughgoing repentance on his part” (104). 22 In just this sense, unconditional forgiveness is a moral “gift” given out of a generosity of spirit or a desire to prioritize encouraging the offender’s moral rehabilitation over collecting the moral compensation that one is owed. Seen in this light, we can appreciate the Balancing Justice and Mercy 451 Both of these elements—justice and mercy—have long been highly esteemed by Jewish thinkers, and so too resolving the tension between them has remained one of the great unresolved issues in Jewish theology and ethics. Those who come down on the side of justice have emphasized that justice is one of the cornerstones of civilized society and one of God’s most precious gifts to us. The rabbis wrote: Rabban Simeon ben Gamaliel said: The world stands on three things—on truth, on justice and on peace, as it is said, “Execute truth, justice and peace within your gates” (Zechariah 8:16). These three are interlinked: When justice is done, truth is achieved, and peace is established (M. Avot 1:18), [as well as] The Holy One said to Israel: My children, as you live, I am exalted because of your intense concern for justice; “The Lord of hosts is exalted through justice.” (Is. 5:16). (Deuteronomy Rabbah 5:7) Where securing justice is our primarily religious duty, a moral commit- ment rooted in our devotion to God, offering forgiveness will forever be conditional on offenders repaying their moral debts, for what system of justice can permit offenders to go free? On the other hand, those who emphasize the pre-eminent value of mercy will note that this is identified as God’s most salient quality. This is articulated pointedly in another rabbinic teaching: Rabbi Yohanan said in the name of Rabbi Yosi: “From where do we know that God prays? As it says ‘I will bring them to my holy mountain, and I will cause them to rejoice in the house of my prayer (Isaiah 56:7). It does not say ‘house of your prayer’ but rather ‘house of my prayer.’ [The Hebrew beit tefilati, is ambiguous and could be read as either “my house of prayer” or “the house of my prayer.”] From here we see that God prays. What does He pray? Rabbi Zutra bar Tuvia said in the name of Rav: ‘May it be my will that my mercy conquer my anger, my mercy be revealed in my attributes, I treat my children with the attribute of compassion, and I go for them beyond the bounds of strict justice.’” (B. Berakhot 7a) God knows that the world cannot long endure without compassion. Where mercy trumps strict justice, unconditional forgiveness must prevail. mistake that some writers have made in suggesting that the person who fails to feel the (supposedly) natural resentment that comes with being harmed is lacking in “self-respect.” The same sort of analysis would lead one to the false conclusion that one who gives a gift to someone fails to feel the (similarly natural) attachment to one’s own possessions. But giving something away—whether one’s moral claim or one’s personal possessions—implies nothing other than putting concern for another above self-interest. For an example of this misguided analysis see Murphy and Hampton 1988, 16. While there are certainly cases, for example that of a battered wife who refuses to seek help or press charges against her abusive husband, where failure to respond retributively may indicate a lack of self-respect, plainly this is not the case in all instances where a victim fails to express resentment. 452 Journal of Religious Ethics This unresolved theological tension between God’s justice and mercy points to what I suspect is a still deeper unresolved tension in Jewish ethics. These alternative theologies of forgiveness reflect two opposing ways of understanding the purpose of our moral action, and this tension is nowhere clearer than in connection with forgiveness. For the question of forgiveness poses what is really the ultimate moral problem in that it requires us to consider what is the proper moral response to immoral behavior. One possibility is that the moral response is to “undo” the immoral behavior by reasserting the demands of conventional morality and requiring the offender to restore the world to the state it was in (as much as possible) prior to the offense. This is what we might call a “restorative” model of morality, one that sees each immoral deed as tilting the scales of the world and requiring a response that tilts them back in the opposite direction, until the world is once again in a state of moral equilibrium. On the other hand, the moral response might be to act so as to create a new moral situation, one in which the distance between the offender and the offended is overcome, in which we do not attempt to reassert the moral values on which society as we know it rests, but rather to create a new kind of society on an altogether different foundation. We might call this a “visionary” model of morality, insofar as it aims not only to transform a single offender, but to transform the world by creating a society that rests not on justice, but on mercy. Just as we treat the offender as if she were more deserving than she is, we act in the world as if it were already a place in which God’s compassion flowed freely among us.23 This, then, is finally what is at stake in the question of forgiveness: does immoral behavior require a moral response that is essentially restorative, that seeks to preserve society as it is, or does it require instead a moral response that is essentially visionary and transformative, that seeks to create a new basis for human relationships? Both views have their merits, as well as their risks. If we adopt a restorative morality, focused on the demands of justice, we risk creating a society in which people who are themselves in need of forgiveness are forever withholding it from others, or threatening to do so. In such a world we are forever keeping track of who is “up” and who is “down,” who is justified and who is not. The demands of justice, after all, are endless, uncompromising and, so to speak, “unforgiving.” But if we adopt a visionary morality, we risk creating a society in which people are no longer held accountable for their misdeeds. In such a world our reach may exceed our grasp, and instead of 23 Schwarzschild 1999 forcefully articulated this visionary thrust in Jewish ethics, which he called “messianic.” As he expressed it, “Messianism as an ethical operator simply declares that, since humanity is to strive to imitate God and thus to endeavor to become like Him, and since they are to undertake these efforts in this world, the ultimate goal of ethics is to establish what is then called ‘the (Messianic) kingdom of God’ on earth” (206). Balancing Justice and Mercy 453 attaining the lofty heights of unconditional compassion we may descend into a situation of moral chaos and unrestrained lawlessness. Neither outcome is particularly appealing, and the choice that Jewish thinkers have made at any given point in history may be a function of which risk they found most unsettling. This analysis of Judaism’s philosophy of forgiveness might well end here. For I think I have shown that there are two quite conflicting and equally compelling ways in which Jewish authorities over the centuries have addressed the question of when and why we have a moral duty to forgive others for their offenses against us. And I have argued that these divergent positions are grounded in still deeper unresolved theological and meta-ethical questions in Jewish tradition, namely, whether we emphasize the obligation to emulate God’s justice or God’s mercy, and whether we think of morality as essentially restorative or visionary. To homogenize these profound and longstanding disagreements within Jewish tradition is both to misrepresent the diversity of Jewish religious-moral thought and to understate the com- plexity of the question at hand. For if forgiveness is sometimes portrayed as the greatest of moral gestures, it is surely also one of the most problematic. I submit that the very ambivalence we find in the Jewish moral teachings presented here reflects the intractability of the problem of forgiveness. But concluding our analysis here does not quite do justice to the subtlety of rabbinic thought on this subject. For, while the rabbis were often willing to let their debates remain unresolved, they were also eager to reconcile opposing views by embracing both poles of a dialectic.24 Plainly, they were well aware that the problem of forgiveness exposed deep divisions within the tradition, too deep, perhaps, to pass over in silence. That impulse to find the middle ground between opposites finds expression in one final text that refers this debate back to the very foundations of the world. In commenting on Genesis 2:4—“The Lord God made earth and heaven”—the rabbis comment: A parable of a king who had cups made of delicate glass. The king said: If I pour hot water into them, they will [expand and] burst; if cold water, they will contract [and break]. What did he do? He mixed hot and cold water, and poured it into them, and so they remained unbroken. Likewise, the Holy One said: If I create the world with the attribute of mercy alone, its sins will be too many; if with justice alone, how could the world be expected to endure? So I will create it with both justice and mercy, and may it endure! (Genesis Rabbah 12:15)25 24 Most famously, in their claim that the (diametrically opposed) views of Hillel and Shammai were both “the words of the living God” (B. Eruvin 13b). 25 Modern biblical scholars have long recognized that Genesis 2:4 links two separate creation narratives. The first, ending with 2:4a, uses “God” (Heb. elohim); the second, beginning with 2:4b, uses “The Lord” (Heb. adonai). Long before the advent of modern biblical criticism, Jewish tradition recognized that these two names for God were associated 454 Journal of Religious Ethics Justice and mercy—both are necessary to sustain the world, but either alone threatens to destroy it. Both the restorative and the visionary responses to immoral behavior are necessary; neither alone is sufficient. So the conflict between the conditional and unconditional views of forgiveness cannot be resolved arbitrarily in favor of one position or the other. Indeed, the rabbis point might well be that each understanding of forgiveness has its place and taken together they hold one another in balance. For they recognized that the moral world we inhabit, like a delicate cup, is ever so fragile; indeed, God created it this way. And so we find ourselves in a world where both justice and mercy are needed in equal measure, and so where forgiveness para- doxically must be both conditional and unconditional.26 REFERENCES Borris-Dunchunstang, Eileen R. 2007 Finding Forgiveness: A 7-Step Program for Letting Go of Anger and Bitterness. New York: McGraw-Hill. Braude, William G. and Israel J. Kapstein, trans. 1981 Tanna Debe Eliyyahu. Philadelphia, Penn.: Jewish Publication Society. Couenhoven, Jesse 2010 “Forgiveness and Restoration: A Theological Exploration.” Journal of Religion 90.2 (April): 148–70. Dorff, Elliot N. 2003 Love Your Neighbor and Yourself. Philadelphia, Penn.: Jewish Publication Society. Enright, Robert D., Suzanne Freedman, and Julio Rique 1998 “The Psychology of Interpersonal Forgiveness.” See Enright and North 1998, 46–62. Enright, Robert D. and Joanna North, eds. 1998 Exploring Forgiveness. Madison, Wisc.: University of Wisconsin Press. Friedman, Philip H. 2009 The Forgiveness Solution: The Whole-Body Rx for Finding True Happiness, Abundant Love, and Inner Peace. San Francisco: Red Wheel/Weiser. with the qualities of justice and mercy respectively. So this verse serves as a particularly apt prompt for the rabbis’ reflection on the necessity of both qualities. I am grateful to Jonathan Crane for calling my attention to this. 26 The foregoing analysis of forgiveness in Judaism should be taken as a corrective to my earlier and less extensive analysis of sources on this question in Newman 1987. I am indebted to Jesse Couenhoven and all the other participants in the conference he organized at Villanova University on “Possibilities of Forgiveness,” Feb. 20–21, 2012, for their insights and their responses to an earlier version of this paper. I have also benefitted from the helpful comments of Jonathan Crane and Geoffrey Claussen and from extended discussion of these issues with my wife, Rabbi Amy Eilberg. Balancing Justice and Mercy 455 Grovier, Trudy 2002 Forgiveness and Revenge. London: Routledge. Haber, Joran Graf 1991 Forgiveness. Savage, Md.: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. Kolnai, Aurel 1973 “Forgiveness.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series 74: 91–106. Luskin, Fred 2002 Forgive For Good. New York: Harper Collins. Maimonides, Moses 1972 A Maimonides Reader. Edited by Isadore Twersky. New York: Behrman House. Murphy, Jeffrie G. 2003 Getting Even: Forgiveness and Its Limits. New York: Oxford Univer- sity Press. Murphy, Jeffrie G. and Jean Hampton 1988 Forgiveness and Mercy. New York: Cambridge University Press. Newman, Louis E. 1987 “The Quality of Mercy: On the Duty to Forgive in Judaic Tradition,” Journal of Religious Ethics 15.2 (Fall): 155–72. 1998 Past Imperatives: Studies in the History and Theory of Jewish Ethics. Albany, N.Y.: State University of New York Press. North, Joanna 1998 “The ‘Ideal’ of Forgiveness: A Philosopher’s Exploration.” See Enright and North 1998, 15–34. Rabbinical Assembly 2010 Mahzor Lev Shalem. New York: The Rabbinical Assembly. Roberts, Robert C. 1995 “Forgivingness.” American Philosophical Quarterly 32.4 (October): 289–306. Sacks, Rabbi Sir Jonathan 2009 The Koren Siddur. Jerusalem: Koren Publishers. Schimmel, Solomon 2002 Wounds Not Healed By Time. New York: Oxford University Press. Schwarzschild, Steven 1999 “On Jewish Eschatology,” In Contemporary Jewish Theology, edited by Elliot N. Dorff and Louis E. Newman, 199–220. New York: Oxford University Press. Statman, Daniel 2012 “A Few Comments on Forgiveness in Jewish Tradition” (Hebrew). In Al Da-at Ha-kahal: Dat V’politika B’hagut Ha-yahadut [With the Permission of the Congregation: Religion and Politics in Jewish Thought]: Festschrift in Honor of Aviezer Ravitzky, edited by Ben- jamin Brown, Menachem Lorberbaum, Avinoam Rosenak and Yedidia Stern, 123–56. Jerusalem: Institute for Israeli Democracy. Telushkin, Joseph 2006 A Code of Jewish Ethics. New York: Bell Tower. 456 Journal of Religious Ethics work_66v7c6pa3jbldnbxyvtrywcxfe ---- Restorative Justice in Uruguay: A Change of Lenses in a Reform of Criminal Justice? Vol.:(0123456789) European Journal for Security Research (2019) 4:131–147 https://doi.org/10.1007/s41125-018-0036-x 1 3 O R I G I N A L A R T I C L E Restorative Justice in Uruguay: A Change of Lenses in a Reform of Criminal Justice? Pablo Galain Palermo1 · Federico del Castillo2 · Ricardo Fraiman3 Received: 19 June 2018 / Accepted: 17 October 2018 / Published online: 28 October 2018 © The Author(s) 2018 Abstract In recent decades, several countries have adopted restorative justice as a means of conflict resolution. While this tradition has deep roots in English-speaking and European countries, the use of restorative justice has been limited in Latin America. In an innovative effort, the Uruguayan Ministry of the Interior developed a restora- tive justice program as part of a comprehensive reform of the criminal justice sys- tem that entailed significant transformations, mainly in the legal system (from an inquisitorial to an adversarial one) and the Uruguayan National Police Force. This article examines this restorative justice initiative in detail, describing the context of its implementation, its implications for the reform of the criminal justice system, its preliminary results and future challenges that lie ahead. Keywords Restorative justice · Criminal procedure · Criminal justice reform · Police 1 Introduction The state has a monopoly over criminal justice, and it performs the role of social control through punishment (retribution) with preventive goals (deterrence) (Albre- cht 2016). Within the continental system—of which the Uruguayan criminal jus- tice system is a party to—deterrence may be either general or specific and is always intended to prevent future crimes against legally protected interests. Specific deter- rence may be positive when its goal is to achieve the re-socialization of the offender or negative when the offender is understood to be dangerous and needs to be sepa- rated from the rest of society. When general deterrence is positive, it reaffirms the value of obeying the norms versus the risk of being subject to punishment, implicit * Pablo Galain Palermo p.galain@mpicc.de 1 Max Planck Institute for International and Foreign Criminal Law, Freiburg, Germany 2 City University of New York, New York City, USA 3 Ministry of the Interior, Montevideo, Uruguay http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1007/s41125-018-0036-x&domain=pdf 132 P. Galain Palermo et al. 1 3 in the act of offending. When negative, it works by intimidating the population through the fear of being arrested, prosecuted and/or convicted (Hassemer 1998, 2002; Streng 1991). How these preventive goals can be achieved through criminal law remains an unresolved issue for criminologists (Albrecht 2001). Any criminal sentence entails a significant imposition on the rights of the accused (Hörnle 2017). Such rationality is tutelary, abstract and retributive and legitimizes the power of the state against those who attempt to break the law since it averts any possible rational dialogue to reach an agreement on conflict resolution (Luhmann 2005). Moreover, it emphasizes punishment, ignoring the will and needs of those affected by a crime (both offenders and victims) and blurring the goal of social paci- fication implicit in the law (Galain Palermo 2016a). Finally, it deliberately ignores academic critiques regarding the negative effects of retribution on rehabilitation and dismisses diverse processes (Galain Palermo 2010) and other means of conflict resolution such as mediation, compensation or reparation (Kerner 1983; Seelmann 2017). A relatively new approach to justice, developed over the last four decades, chal- lenges such a rationale. It is restorative justice, which focuses on the wishes and needs of those involved in a conflict. This movement puts forward new questions. Instead of asking “who committed an offense?”, what really matters is who was harmed, how they were harmed and what were the consequences. Restorative jus- tice seeks to understand how to solve the conflict, and how victims and offenders can jointly bring the conflict to an end (Zehr 2004). A critical issue is whether this new approach can complement the current juridical practices of criminal law, or if it demands a drastic paradigm shift (to paraphrase Zehr 2004) a “change of lenses” for the whole criminal justice system. Moreover, if such a change were to take place, what would this really mean and what transformations would it entail? This article aims to shed light on these questions by examining a restorative jus- tice program implemented by the Uruguayan Ministry of the Interior in the context of a comprehensive reform of the criminal justice system. The article starts by dis- cussing the conceptual implications of restorative justice. Then, it describes the con- text of implementation, examining victimization and fear of crime data in Uruguay, as well as the juridical context in which the program is taking place. The program is then described in detail, with a focus on the actions undertaken and the preliminary results, as well as its connection to the reform of Uruguay’s Code of Criminal Proce- dure. Finally, the article discusses the potential outcomes of this program within the context of the new code, and it outlines some questions to guide future examinations of Uruguay’s experience of restorative justice. 2 What is Restorative Justice? Restorative justice is not a contemporary practice, but a revival of traditional conflict resolution practices, characterized by being local, close to people and more effective than mainstream methods when it comes to dealing with the interpersonal relation- ships behind crimes (Jaamdar 2017). The roots of the contemporary restorative jus- tice movement can be found in pre-industrial societies. Oriental philosophies such as 133 1 3 Restorative Justice in Uruguay: A Change of Lenses in a Reform… the Vedas, Buddhism, Taoism and Confucianism, ancient Western civilizations like Greece and Rome and the indigenous peoples of Oceania, all resorted to restorative practices to avoid retaliation between individuals, families and tribes (Braithwaite 2002; Gavrielides 2011; Huxley 1939; Albrecht et  al. 2006; Sherman and Strang 2010). For example, countries with ancient cultural roots such as India consider restorative justice as “justice that heals” (Raina and Kumar 2017). The very idea of restorative justice embraces values such as healing, compassion, mercy, mediation, forgiveness, reconciliation and sanctions (Consedine 1995). In spite of its ancient roots, the concept of restorative justice is still subject to debate in the modern world, and it is hard to find a universal definition that encompasses all the perspectives cov- ered by this concept. However, the definition proposed by Marshall (1996) is widely accepted in the specialized literature: Restorative justice is a process whereby all the parties with a stake in a par- ticular offence come together to resolve collectively how to deal with the after- math of the offence and its implications for the future (Marshall 1996: 37). Zehr (2004) proposes an alternative definition emphasizing the purpose of the method of healing: Restorative justice is a process to involve, to the extent possible, those who have a stake in a specific offense to collectively identify and address harms, needs and obligations in order to heal and put things as right as possible (Zehr 2004: 37) Others emphasize the process of restoration, defining restorative justice: …as a process where those primarily affected by an incident of wrong-doing come together to share their feelings, describe how they were affected and develop a plan to repair the harm done or prevent reoccurrence (McCold and Watchel 2002: 113). The inclusive spirit of these—and other—definitions results in differential appli- cations. In spite of these differences, it could be said that modern restorative justice is an approach to the affairs of criminal law that focuses its efforts on repairing the harm caused by criminal activity without blurring the lines between criminal and civil law (Hirsch 1969, 1990). It has been calculated that restorative practices are currently implemented in approximately 100 countries, with almost 23 different types of prison-based restora- tive programs in 84 countries, and over 300 victim-offender mediation programs in the USA alone, with a further 700 plus in Europe (Gavrielides 2015). Most of these programs are linked to the assumption that punishment is a chronic problem and recognize the failure of detention and incarceration practices as standard forms of punishment (Kenny and Leonard 2014). In contrast to the standard criminal justice system based on the principle of retribution, restorative justice follows methodical steps to repair the harm done to the victim. The outcome is an agreement freely entered into by the parties that repairs the harm caused (Galain Palermo 2010, 2016a). According to this rationale, imprisonment and other sentences (house arrest, 134 P. Galain Palermo et al. 1 3 probation and alternative sentences) are not necessarily suitable for the preven- tion of recidivism and making reparations to victims, since they are not allowed to participate in the sentencing process. Its advocates argue that the mainstream view in the criminal justice system of victims and offenders is mistaken: it is not about enemies or people with different motivations, interests and stakeholdings, but about people who may work together to deal better with the aftermath of harm. In fact, it is argued that this mainstream assumption can even promote a desire for retaliation from the victim and society toward the offender, ignoring the fact that many offend- ers see themselves as victims (Sherman and Strang 2007). Restorative justice places victims at the core of the justice process. Such an idea does not require an entirely different criminal justice system, but a reform that includes restorative agreements pursuant to the “material truth,” as sought by the investigative process, plus a “consensual truth” between the parties. This implies the inclusion of alternative solutions and mechanisms that strive for social harmony, going one step further than material truth in seeking reconciliation and pacification (consensual truth). Although all this may sound strange regarding regular crimes, it has been gaining acceptance in the area of transitional justice, where restorative approaches are better suited to offering adequate mechanisms for reconciliation (Knust 2013; Baumann 2012; Galain Palermo 2016b; Fischer and Simić 2016). In this sense, truth commissions and similar political mechanisms of truth-seeking and reconciliation are more suitable than the traditional criminal justice system in deal- ing with transitional justice processes, since “reparations should be linked to the process of truth recovery” (Maepa 2005: 75). It is important to note, however, that restorative justice is not the only mechanism available to impose proportionate pun- ishment for such a class of serious crimes (Olásolo and Galain 2018). In practice, restorative justice is used to deal with minor and mid-level offenses. However, in order to achieve restorative goals, these mechanisms should go beyond minor crimes, juvenile and first-time offenders, “with the aim of providing restora- tive outcomes to a maximum number of crimes in a maximum number of possi- ble situations and contexts, including those whose voluntary agreements are not possible and coercion is needed” (Walgrave 2001: 34). There are no philosophi- cal obstacles to restorative justice being used for more serious crimes and felonies, such as homicide, rape, domestic violence or even human rights violations. But for that to happen, a change of lenses is required in criminal law, to no longer focus just on making offenders responsible but rather on having them taking responsibil- ity for what they have done. Unlike the notion of accountability embedded in the mainstream criminal justice system, restorative justice is based on the willingness to accept responsibility (Foley 2014). Therefore, until such a change arises, the exten- sion of restorative mechanisms is unlikely. A key actor embedded in the restorative process is the community. Any restora- tive approach needs to re-involve the community in the conflict resolution process since conflicts that once belonged to it were “stolen” by public officers (Christie 1977). The role of the community is, however, controversial. While some argue that communities and offenders share responsibility for the loss caused by the crime committed in the first place, others point to community members as “indirect vic- tims” of the crime. But which community members can participate in restorative 135 1 3 Restorative Justice in Uruguay: A Change of Lenses in a Reform… practices? Any individual interested in contributing to fulfilling the restorative prac- tice by supporting either the offender or the victim. While preparing a restorative intervention, “facilitators need to identify the most appropriate ‘community’ to include” (Cunneen and Hoyle 2010: 17). In any circumstances, the whole commu- nity has to contribute to the reintegration of the offender. Even police officers can participate in a restorative intervention as community members. In summary, restorative justice can and should be included in the framework of the mainstream criminal justice system. However, more empirical research is required in order to determine what restorative justice is. Such research will facili- tate comparisons with mainstream mechanisms of conflict resolution to determine which one achieves better outcomes. 3 Background Uruguay has traditionally been one of the safest countries in Latin America, regis- tering crime rates significantly lower than its counterparts on the continent. Still, a consistent increase in major crimes over the last thirty years, tied to a growing public concern about crime and violence, forced the country to engage in a com- prehensive reform of its criminal justice system. Some of these changes involved restorative justice as a means to avoid incarceration in the context of the reform of Uruguay’s Code of Criminal Procedure. Before examining this reform in detail, it is worth providing some context on recent national crime trends. Recent available data show that Uruguay has a moderate victimization rate com- pared to 18 Latin American countries. Despite a recent increase in this indicator, Uruguay has traditionally registered low levels of victimization (Lagos and Dam- mert 2012). However, in contrast to this, when fear of crime is examined, the coun- try shows a disproportionate public concern considering its moderate victimization rate. Eighteen percent of Uruguayans fear becoming victims of crime, a figure sig- nificantly higher than in Venezuela, Mexico, Argentina or the Dominican Republic, all countries with some of the highest crime rates on the continent (Corporación Latinobarometro 2016). Such incongruence is not surprising. Crime trends have been rising in Uruguay for over four decades. For example, when police data for homicide, robbery and theft crime trends are examined—the three main crime categories in Uruguay—the problem is clearly visible. Although 2016 showed a slight decline in homicide and robbery, all three types of crime show consistent growth in recent years (Ministerio del Interior 2016). While police data have inherent limitations such as under repre- sentation or misreporting, it helps to illustrate the failure of the Uruguayan criminal justice system to properly address crime problems, as well as the consolidation of crime as one of the main problems the country faces (Fig. 1). When crime has a social background, criminal policy must be inclusive. In coun- tries like Uruguay, where there is a marked contrast between victimization and fear of crime, community involvement in conflict resolution prevents potential retaliation and fear of crime from growing, enhancing the positive public perception regard- ing the intervention of the justice system. This, however, does not exactly apply to 136 P. Galain Palermo et al. 1 3 Uruguay, where a lack of trust in law enforcement and justice cannot be explained by high corruption indices, since the country has the lowest rate of corruption in the region. According to the International Corruption Perceptions Index, Uruguay is ranked 23rd in the world as the least corrupt country in Latin America (Transpar- ency 2017). Another significant problem in Uruguay is its disproportionately high rate of incarceration. With a rate of 321 per 100,000 and 11,149 people behind bars in 2017, Uruguay has the highest incarceration rate in South America (World Prison Brief 2017). With deprivation of liberty being the most common punishment, Uru- guayan prisons are suffering from overcrowding and violence (Fig. 2). In a scenario like this, fear becomes the defining feature of a normative system that violates human rights and the fundamental guarantees of its citizens. Public fear of the criminal justice system and its operators must be turned into trust (Baker et  al. 2000), a goal that can only be achieved through a system based on dialogue, free will, reparation, reintegration, participation, inclusion and reconciliation (Jiang 2016). All these principles need to be translated into the justice system and its pro- cedures. This will not be an easy task and requires a change of lenses through which the world is viewed by its citizens, who must leave state paternalism behind and adopt responsible post-crime conduct toward both criminals and victims (Galain Palermo 2010). Change must also take place in the “mind” of the administrators of justice, but this will most likely arise as a consequence of the first one (Fig. 3). There is another factor which could contribute to re-signifying and dignify- ing the relationship between state and citizens. It relates to the first two (and only) 214 218 231 197 200 190 202 194 221 226 205 199 267 260 268 293 265 0 50 100 150 200 250 300 350 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 2008 2009 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 Re po rt s Year Homicide 2000-2016 Fig. 1 Homicide 2000–2016. Source: Ministry of the Interior of Uruguay 137 1 3 Restorative Justice in Uruguay: A Change of Lenses in a Reform… 6751 6147 8483 6933 7000 8352 8867 9173 10705 11391 13829 15003 15414 16718 20114 21135 20348 0 5000 10000 15000 20000 25000 20002001200220032004200520062007200820092010201120122013201420152016 Re po rt s Year Robbery 2000-2016 Fig. 2 Robbery 2000–2016. Source: Ministry of the Interior of Uruguay 60608 68833 76108 89853 98409 104902 101985 99842 105629 94508 95269 97573 96827 97465 105892 109139 114129 0 20000 40000 60000 80000 100000 120000 20002001200220032004200520062007200820092010201120122013201420152016 Re po rt Year The� 2000-2016 Fig. 3 Theft 2000–2016. Source: Ministry of the Interior of Uruguay 138 P. Galain Palermo et al. 1 3 condemnatory sentences of the Inter-American Court of Human Rights in 20111 and the “amicable agreement” between Uruguay and the Inter-American Commission on Human Rights in 2009, by which a reform of the Uruguayan Code of Criminal Pro- cedure was agreed upon.2 This raised awareness among Uruguayan citizens about their capacity to seek recourse in international human rights courts to act against the state when it—either through action or omission—violates fundamental norms aimed at their protection (Galain Palermo 2013). Such awareness could favorably influence both public authorities and citizens to take the next step and pursue more human, less violent and more participative ways of conflict resolution in an inclusive and restorative framework of human relationships (Table 1). But this is not the only conceptual challenge to restorative justice becom- ing a new science (social, legal), as there are wide ranging and disparate views and arguments on the subject which vary according to one’s philosophical van- tage point such as abolitionism, Christian philosophy, the restorative movement and economic neoliberalism applied to penal theory (Reggio 2010). This topic leads us to the question as to whether we need police officers, prosecutors and judges acting as guarantors, or rather, a community justice system that requires Table 1 Victimization rate per country 2016 (Latin America). Source: Corporación Latinobarómetro (2016) Country Victimiza- tion rate (%) Venezuela 48 Mexico 46 Argentina 41 Dominican Republic 41 Peru 39 Honduras 38 Brazil 37 Chile 37 Guatemala 36 Paraguay 35 Uruguay 35 Costa Rica 35 Colombia 34 Panama 32 El Salvador 31 Nicaragua 31 Bolivia 30 Ecuador 29 1 Case Gelman v Uruguay and case Barbani Duarte and others v Uruguay. 2 Case Jorge, José and Dante Peirano Baso v Uruguay. Resolution 86/09, Inter-American Commission on Human Rights. 139 1 3 Restorative Justice in Uruguay: A Change of Lenses in a Reform… neighbors, social referents, psychologists or social workers acting as mediators. As can be seen, it is not just a question of substituting the binomial crime sanc- tion for conflict reparation, but also of fundamental questions that facilitate such a conceptual evolution within a juridical framework. This ensures the voluntary participation of the parties in conflict resolutions as well as the constitutional premises of equality and legality. Due process is not just concerned with dealing with the asymmetry between the parties in conflict resolution processes but also assigns universal validity to the agreements reached. This means that they have a similar recognition and weight as any other judgement of the courts and are considered to have the force of res judicata. Otherwise, those who claim that we would be faced with an inter-partes proceeding, which could not take the place of penal resolutions would be right (Galain Palermo 2010). In order to address some of the issues just described, the Ministry of the Inte- rior of Uruguay, the government agency responsible for the oversight of the Uru- guayan National Police Force (UNP), launched a pilot restorative justice program aimed at mitigating neighborhood conflicts and their consequences (del Castillo et  al. 2015). This endeavor, which started in 2013, was framed within an ambi- tious reform of both the UNP, and Uruguay’s Code of Criminal Procedure. This has resulted in the institutionalization of restorative justice within the criminal justice system of Uruguay. The actions undertaken are outlined in the following section (Table 2). Table 2 Fear of crime per country 2016 (Latin America). Source: Corporación Latinobarómetro (2016) Country Fear of crime (%) Guatemala 26 Nicaragua 19 Uruguay 18 Colombia 17 Panama 17 Honduras 14 Costa Rica 14 El Salvador 14 Dominican Republic 14 Argentina 9 Chile 8 Mexico 8 Bolivia 8 Brazil 8 Venezuela 8 Ecuador 7 Peru 6 Paraguay 6 140 P. Galain Palermo et al. 1 3 4 Restorative Justice in Uruguay The UNP’s experience of restorative justice dates back to 2013, when the Min- istry of the Interior drafted a pilot restorative justice program to be developed in three police precincts in Montevideo: precincts 15th, 19th and 25th. (Precinct 17th was added to these in 2017.) In general terms, the objectives of this pro- gram were to consolidate an institutional methodology for the peaceful resolution of social conflicts in Uruguay and to restore the social relationships broken by crimes; in other words, to repair the harm caused to victims of conflicts and vio- lence. To achieve such goals, a series of actions were undertaken. First of all, starting in 2013, dozens of police officers enrolled in a restora- tive justice-training program delivered by a team of professors from the Univer- sity of Cambridge. As a result, 36 officers from Uruguay’s police were qualified to develop restorative justice conferences in the country. Unlike other restorative justice programs, conferences are led by police officers acting as facilitators. At the same time, complimentary workshops and events around this initiative were conducted with agents of Uruguay’s criminal justice system (judges, prosecutors, public defenders and police officers) to raise awareness about it. Prior to police officers addressing restorative justice cases, a process of dia- logue between the Ministry of the Interior and the Judiciary began in 2014 aimed at building a consensus and adequately implementing restorative justice in com- pliance with Uruguay’s legal framework. This dialogue resulted in a memoran- dum of agreement that enabled the Ministry to work with extra-judicial cases, meaning those cases reported to the police and dismissed by the Judiciary. Fol- lowing this agreement, in 2015 the Ministry of the Interior started working with extra-judicial cases in the 15th, 19th and 25th precincts of Montevideo. While the number of cases was low at the beginning, this helped to progressively build pro- ficiency among restorative justice practitioners. This experience took place prior to the enactment of a new code of criminal procedure in Uruguay, aimed at addressing problems and inefficiencies associ- ated with the inquisitorial system. The timely discussion on the new code offered a good opportunity to consolidate restorative justice in Uruguay as a means of diverting cases from sentencing, and therefore institutionalizing and raising the status of the agreement between the Ministry of the Interior and the Judiciary at the level of the Code of Criminal Procedure. Some of the implications of this sce- nario are discussed below. 5 Restorative Justice in the New Uruguayan Criminal Procedure Code The Uruguayan Parliament enacted a new criminal procedure system (Law 19,293 of 2014) which came into force in late 2017, as a consequence of the previously cited amicable agreement between Uruguay and the Inter-American Commis- sion on Human Rights. This agreement helped (at least normatively) leave behind 141 1 3 Restorative Justice in Uruguay: A Change of Lenses in a Reform… the inquisitorial system of a single judge, who leads the entire investigation and sentencing, put in place during the last civil–military dictatorship (1973–1985). This system was replaced by an accusatorial, adversarial, oral public system, in compliance with the judicial standards of the American Convention on Human Rights. Among the main reforms, the new system introduced was that preven- tive detention was no longer considered as an advance punishment and procedural rule, becoming instead a protective measure, the use of which must be justified by procedural matters. Perceptive preventive detention after the commission of a second crime was also repealed. At the same time, the victim now participates in the mainstream criminal procedure system, as well as in the newly enacted alter- native procedures. The new code was modified in 2016 by adding an extension to the principle of opportunity to include alternative methods of conflict resolution (articles 382–401) as well as the abbreviated criminal trial (article 272). Not only does the new reform recognize the rights of the victim regarding the gathering of incriminatory evidence by the Public Ministry (articles 79–81), but also achieves reparatory agreements with the author of the crime through the use of penal or extra-judicial mediation. The chapter “Alternative Methods of Conflict Resolution” (Arts. 382 ff), instead of a criminal investigation by the public ministry, provides for the diversion of the case into a mediation process that facilitates an encounter between the victim and the offender aimed at reaching agreement on reparatory measures. The reparations to the victim could also lead to the so-called conditional suspension of the process, whereby the prosecutor can suspend an ongoing investigation through an agreement with the perpetrator of a crime. These procedural figures build on the voluntary admission of responsibility by the author and are applied only if there is no public interest in a criminal prosecution and the crimes are not of a grievous nature (arti- cles 383 and 393). Thus, two principles justify the extension of the discretionary principle: lack of public interest in prosecutions and the crime being a relatively less serious one. These principles, which lead to a withdrawal of penal action, cannot be solely deter- mined by legislators, but must instead be defined on a case-by-case basis. In order to resort to the discretionary principle, an agreement on the conditions and obligations regarding the reparations for the harm caused must be made between the parties. It must be acknowledged that sometimes the diversion into these alternative meas- ures makes the complete clarification of the case impossible, which is a goal of the principle of legality itself and not a goal of the discretionary principle. This aims to fulfill a procedural function of celerity and efficiency based on selection instead of the material function of truth-seeking. The penal process is itself a burden that the accused must bear (whether innocent or guilty) so that the lack of interest in pros- ecution and the crime not being grievous in nature enable the justice administration to disregard a process that is expensive in terms of freedom, and unlikely to reveal the material truth, opting instead for the consensual truth. Criminal procedure reform always leaves the door open to the possibility of start- ing a trial in the standard way when no agreement has been reached regarding the alternatives, or when such an agreement has not been honored. In such case, either a new criminal trial starts, or the suspended one is revived. Depending on the nature 142 P. Galain Palermo et al. 1 3 of the crime, when clarification of the case is required, criminal procedure should take precedence as the general interest is served by prosecution. The conditional suspension of the process—an agreement between the prosecutor and the defendant takes place somewhere between the process being formalized, the pressing of charges or the dismissal of the case—shall not proceed when the mini- mum sentence for the crime is in excess of 3 years in prison; when the defendant is already serving a sentence; and when the accused is facing another process involv- ing conditional suspension (article 384). This feature is not an example of restorative justice but rather of negotiations between the parties that do not necessarily include the victim (although the possibility of mediation between the author of a crime and its victim is provided for in article 386c) as one of the conditions or obligations that could be agreed upon. However, the reparatory agreement provided for in articles 393 onward could be considered as an instrument that is closer to restorative justice since from the moment of the formalization of the investigation, and throughout the process, both defendant and victim could subscribe to a material or symbolic reparatory agreement that will be made available to the judge for his consideration, with the intervention of the public ministry. It is worth mentioning that these agreements are only possi- ble for less serious offenses, non-intentional crimes, those subject to fines, assault— with the exception of aggravated assault—property crimes, indictable crimes at the request of the victim—with the exception of sex crimes—and crimes against honor. 6 Implementation and Preliminary Results Through the reparatory agreements introduced in the new Code of Criminal Pro- cedure, restorative justice acquired a formal status in Uruguay, something that pos- itively impacted the pilot program launched by the Ministry. What initially func- tioned as a means of addressing cases dismissed by the Judiciary has now acquired legal status as an alternative method of conflict resolution. This has led to the con- solidation of restorative justice within Uruguay’s criminal justice system, and con- sequently a significant increase in the program’s caseload. Nevertheless, considering the small number of cases diverted to mediation in the juvenile criminal system—a mechanism that has been available for more than two decades—we must note the difference between laws on the books and laws in action. A relevant question for future research is that of why, even when conciliation mechanisms for the resolution of social conflict have been established since Uruguay’s first Constitution (1830, Art. 107), it has seldom been used in the country. While such a question is beyond the scope of this article, it is important to raise it in order to point out how long it usually takes for these types of initiatives to achieve full implementation in Uruguay. The mechanisms outlined over the following paragraphs describe the program’s implementation in the context of the inquisitorial criminal procedure code that was in force until late 2017. While the program now operates in the same fashion, some things have changed. For example, prosecutors have replaced judges, and commu- nication between facilitators and judicial operators has improved. Nevertheless, the mechanisms are, in general, very similar to each other. 143 1 3 Restorative Justice in Uruguay: A Change of Lenses in a Reform… In practice, the program operates as follows. Facilitators start by looking at all incident reports received by the police using the information management software of the UNP. The search is conducted on a monthly basis for extra-judicial cases reg- istered during the previous month at the precincts in which the program operates (15th, 17th, 19th and 25th). Cases are filtered according to their “judicial resolu- tion,” meaning whether a judge (now a prosecutor) has made a ruling on it. A set of “potential cases” results from this filtering, which are cases where a judicial decision has been made. These are filtered again to discard cases that: (a) involve sentenced people; (b) police officers or minors are involved in; (c) involve domestic violence; (d) there is no apparent harm involved; (d) do not include any means of contacting the parties involved. Following this selection, a set of “feasible cases” is obtained. These filters are not arbitrarily applied but follow the memorandum of agreement with the Judiciary, and the recommendations of international experts and advisers who advise on the program’s implementation. Later on, feasible cases are filtered to determine which of them fulfill the neces- sary requirements to conduct a conference (for example, if both parties can be con- tacted). A list of “workable” cases is then obtained. Facilitators contact the offender first. If he or she agrees to participate in the conference, then facilitators contact the victim. If both parties are willing to move forward, a preparatory interview is coordinated separately with each of them. During this interview, facilitators explain the conference in detail to participants, learn about the conflict and make sure their interest in participating in the conference is entirely voluntary. If both offender and victim confirm their voluntary interest in participating, a conference is then scheduled. The conference takes place in a neutral room, properly conditioned to develop a conference (sober decoration, chairs arranged in a circular fashion, water dispenser and disposable tissues available, etc.). The conference is not limited to those directly involved in the incident. If there is a consensus between victim and offender, each party is allowed to invite others to the conference. They may be people indirectly involved in the incident, relatives, friends or neighbors, whom participants believe could either add relevant information or provide support to them over the course of the conference. The conference is facilitated by one leading facilitator supported by one assistant facilitator, and it ends with the celebration of a signed agreement drawn up and agreed to by the participants. Both parties commit themselves to fulfilling the agreement over a period of time determined on a case-by-case basis. After the conference, facilitators engage in follow-up actions in the next 15, 30 and 90 days after the agreement was signed or determine whether it is being fulfilled or not. Data from April 2015 to June 2017, made available by the Ministry shows that facilitators found 466 feasible cases, 51 of which led to a conference (Firpo 2017). This is an effectiveness ratio of approximately 1–9 cases in which a conference was held. Data for 2016 (disaggregated data was not made available for 2017) show that 25 of the 51 conferences held during that year were concluded with a successful agreement after the conference. This is the best possible scenario, where the conflict disappears after the intervention. At the same time, an agreement was signed but not fulfilled and conflict persists in 14% of cases, in 11% the agreement was signed but 144 P. Galain Palermo et al. 1 3 not fulfilled, although conflict disappeared, and in the remaining 11%, an agreement was not even reached. While these figures seem promising, it is important to state that serious flaws exist regarding the program’s data. First, data are not systemati- cally but rather arbitrarily registered following specific requests from the authorities. This hinders potential assessments of the program’s implementation and results, as data are not periodically collated and analyzed. Second, data are not disaggregated, which also makes process and outcome assessments difficult. For example, updated data on case types were not made available and only exist at a raw level. These are serious limitations to be addressed in order to determine the failure or success of the program in fulfilling its goals. However, while a systematic evaluation of the program remains to be done, pre- liminary data—although weak—seem promising. If restorative justice is contrib- uting to the mitigation and prevention of conflicts in a pilot program in the juris- dictions of four police precincts, similar results could be achieved in others. The implications of this preliminary data are discussed in the following section. 7 Discussion and Conclusions Some concluding remarks can be made on the basis of these preliminary results. First, referenced interview data for 2016 show that 25 out of 39 conferences suc- ceeded in solving the original conflict (Firpo 2017). While this number may not have a significant impact on the criminal justice system as a whole, the potential impact of this pilot program should not be underestimated. It must be stated, however, that this is true as far as the original conflict is concerned. Data are not available regard- ing the potential future preventive effects of the program. A follow-up study involv- ing conference participants could shed some light on this matter. A positive impact of the program on the experiences of those who participated in the conferences can also be seen. Anecdotal data collected by the Ministry show satisfaction with the restorative process among those who participated in the confer- ences, who have also declared they were treated with seriousness and respect by facilitators (Firpo 2017). This degree of satisfaction with the restorative process is consistent with the outcomes of other restorative programs reported on in the spe- cialized literature (Latimer et al. 2005; Sherman et al. 2005). Second, given the bottleneck in Uruguay’s criminal justice system, which results in only a few cases being resolved judicially, restorative justice could act as an ideal complement to the mainstream judicial process. This is sustained on at least two grounds. First, in normative terms, preventive and retributive goals can be fulfilled not only through standard sanctions but also through mediation agreements. Second, international experience shows that restorative justice can be implemented at differ- ent stages of the judicial process, i.e., prior to, in tandem with or following sentenc- ing, and also as an alternative measure to incapacitation (Sherman and Strang 2010). Such flexibility of restorative justice programs is particularly relevant in Uruguay, given the previously noted limitations of the judicial system to properly address the volume of conflicts in the country. 145 1 3 Restorative Justice in Uruguay: A Change of Lenses in a Reform… Third, all of the above have implications in the context of the implementation of the new Code of Criminal Procedure in Uruguay. Criminal justice cannot be understood in terms of a dichotomy between general crime prevention and specific prevention as it is a matter of choosing between the needs of the community and the needs of the per- petrator. The reform of the Uruguayan Code of Criminal Procedure has facilitated the participation of the victim, allowing justice operators (prosecutors) to resort to restora- tive justice as an alternative way of conflict and dispute resolution. Restorative justice can meet the expectations of those involved in the conflict and of the community, with- out one being absorbed by the other. Nothing prevents Uruguay from using restorative justice to accomplish both general and specific prevention goals, and at the same time increase the level of satisfaction with the justice system of those who participate in restorative practices (victims and offenders). Whether this is actually adopted in prac- tice by the Uruguayan judicial system remains to be seen, but its formalization in law is undoubtedly an important step toward social harmony and peaceful coexistence among the citizenry. Finally, it is important to pose some questions to guide future examinations of the process of adoption of restorative justice by Uruguay’s criminal justice system. The first is to what extent will Uruguay apply the recently created alternative measures to restore broken social relations, or just to speed up agreements between the prosecutor and counsel for the defense. Secondly, in a context of a high fear of crime and perma- nent calls for harsh punishments for ordinary crimes, it is worth asking to what extent Uruguay’s society and the institutions of its criminal justice system are prepared to accept and adopt a different approach to punishment. Thirdly, will all these transforma- tions result in an improvement of the capacity of the system to properly address violent incidents and conflict, while at the same time preventing future incidents and improv- ing citizens’ satisfaction with the justice system? All these questions are of importance and should guide future investigations of the experience of Uruguay’s criminal justice system with restorative justice. Any norma- tive reform in this field will not be successful if the need for real change in the mecha- nisms for achieving justice and social harmony is not understood by justice operators and society as a whole. Only a transformation in how citizens think—a process that starts by increasing the visibility of the problem, educating, advertising and explaining the disadvantages to which all citizens (not just criminals) are subjected to—leads to an actual change of lenses in Uruguay’s criminal justice system. Resistance and lack of interest demonstrated by both legislators and judicial officials against restorative prac- tices will only cease when the benefits of the new system are acknowledged and made visible (even if it is only complementary to the mainstream model) and when every actor involved in the justice process understands that this new model does not signify a loss of power, but rather a redefinition that leads to better access to justice for all. Acknowledgements Open access funding provided by Max Planck Society. Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Interna- tional License (http://creat iveco mmons .org/licen ses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons license, and indicate if changes were made. http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ 146 P. Galain Palermo et al. 1 3 References Albrecht HJ (2001) Criminal preventive risk assessment in the law-making procedure. Final report on the research project 1999/FAL/140. Freiburg: Max-Planck-Institute für ausländisches und internation- ales Strafrecht Albrecht HJ (2016) Strafrechtliche Sozialkontrolle, Kriminalität und die Kriminologie. In: Albrecht HJ (ed) Kriminalität, Kriminalitätskontrolle, Strafvollzug und Menschenrechte. Internationales Kollo- quium zum gedenken an Professor Dr. Günther Kaiser am 23. Januar 2009, Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, pp 81–100 Albrecht HJ, Simon JM, Rezaei H, Rohne HC, Kiza E (2006) Conflicts and conflict resolution in Middle Eastern societies- between tradition and modernity. Duncker & Humblot, Berlin Baker M, Nienstedt B, Everett R, McCleary R (2000) The impact of a crime wave: perceptions, fear, and confidence in the Police. In: Ditton J, Farrall S (eds) The fear of crime. Ashgate, Aldershot, pp 151–167 Baumann E (2012) Striking a balance between justice and peace: restorative justice in sates of transition. In: Grönning, Jacobsen J (eds) Restorative justice and criminal justice. Exploring the relationship. Santérus Academic Press, Sweden, pp 123–168 Braithwaite J (2002) Restorative justice and responsive regulation. Oxford University Press, Oxford Christie N (1977) Conflicts as property. Br J Criminol 17(1):1–15 Consedine J (1995) Restorative justice: healing the effects of crime. Ploughshares, Lyttelton Corporación Latinobarómetro (2016) Informe 2016. Report, Corporación Latinobarómetro, Santiago de Chile Cunneen C, Hoyle C (2010) Debating restorative justice. Bloomsbury Publishing, Oxford del Castillo F, Fraiman R, Galain Palermo P (2015) Aproximación a la justicia restaurativa en Uruguay. Espacio abierto 23:100–105 Firpo E (2017) Ministerio del Interior. Reseña de actividades en desarrollo. Report, Ministerio del Inte- rior, Uruguay Fischer M, Simić O (2016) Transitional Justice and Reconciliation. Lessons from the Balkans. Routledge, Abingdom Foley T (2014) Developing restorative justice jurisprudence. Rethinking responses to criminal wrongdo- ing. Ashgate, Farnham Galain Palermo P (2010) La reparación del daño a la víctima del delito. Tirant lo Blanch, Valencia Galain Palermo P (2013) La influencia de las decisiones de los órganos del sistema interamericano de protección de los derechos humanos en el derecho penal de Uruguay. In: Ambos K, Malarino E, Steiner C (eds) Sistema interame-ricano de protección de los derechos humanos y derecho penal internacional. Fundación Konrad Adenauer, Bogotá, pp 399–443 Galain Palermo P (2016a) Justicia Restaurativa y Sistema Penal ¿Cambio de paradigma o nuevas her- ramientas de la justicia penal?. Universidad Católica del Uruguay, Montevideo Galain Palermo P (2016b) ¿Justicia de transición? Mecanismos políticos y jurídicos para la elaboración del pasado. Tirant lo Blanch, Valencia Gavrielides T (2011) Restorative practices: From the early societies to the 1970s. Internet J Criminol. Retrieved from http://www.inter netjo urnal ofcri minol ogy.com/Gavri elide s_Resto rativ e_Pract ices_ IJC_Novem ber_2011.pdf Gavrielides T (2015) The psychology of restorative justice. Managing the power within. Ashgate, Farnham Hassemer W (1998) Variationen der positiven Generalprävention. In: Schünemann B et al. (eds) Positive Generalprävention kritische Analysen im deutsch-en-glischen Dialog. Uppsala Symposium 1996. Heidelberg: Müller Hassemer W (2002) Darf der strafende Staat verurteilte bessern wollen? Resozialisierung im Rahmen positiver Generalprävention. In: Prittwitz C et  al (eds) Festschrift für Klaus Lürsenn. Nomos, Baden-Baden, pp 221–240 Hirsch H (1969) Zur Abgrenzung von Strafrecht und Zivilrecht. In: Sockelmann F et al (eds) Festschrift für Karl Engish. Geburtstag, Klostermann, Frankfurt, pp 304–326 Hirsch H (1990) Wiedergutmachung des Schadens im Rahmen des materiellen Strafrechts. Zeitschrift für die gesamte Strafrechtswissenschaft 102(3):534–562 Hörnle T (2017) Zwecke und Rechtfertigung staatlicher Strafe. In: Saliger F (ed) Rechtsstaatliches Stra- frecht. Festschrift für Ulfrid Neumann zum 70. Geburtstag. Müller, Heidelberg, pp 593–605 http://www.internetjournalofcriminology.com/Gavrielides_Restorative_Practices_IJC_November_2011.pdf http://www.internetjournalofcriminology.com/Gavrielides_Restorative_Practices_IJC_November_2011.pdf 147 1 3 Restorative Justice in Uruguay: A Change of Lenses in a Reform… Huxley E (1939) Red strangers. Chatto and Windus, London Jaamdar SM (2017) Restorative justice in India: old and new. In: Thilagaraj et al (eds) Restorative justice in India. Traditional practice and contemporary applications. Springer, Cham, pp 41–75 Jiang J (2016) Criminal reconciliation in contemporary china. An empirical and analytical enquiry. Elgar, Cheltenham Kenny P, Leonard L (2014) The sustainability of restorative justice. Emerald, Bingley Kerner H (1983) Diversion statt Strafe? Probleme und Gefahren einer neuen Strategie strafrechtlicher Sozial Kontrolle. Kriminalistik Verlag, Heidelberg Knust N (2013) Entwicklung eines pluralistischen Rechtsmodells am Beispiel des ruan-dischen Völker- mordes. Max-Planck-Institut, Berlin Lagos M and Dammert L (2012) La Seguridad ciudadana. El principal problema de América Latina. San- tiago de Chile: Corporación Latinobarómetro, Santiago de Chile Latimer J, Dowden C, Muise D (2005) The effectiveness of restorative justice practices: a meta-analysis. The prison journal 85(2):127–144 Luhmann N (2005) Soziologische Aufklärung 6. Die Soziologie und der Mensch, 2 Auflage, Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften, Wiesbaden Maepa T (2005) The truth and reconciliation commission as a model of restorative justice. In: Maepa T (ed) Beyond retribution. Prospects for restorative justice in South Africa. Institute for Security Stud- ies, Pretoria, pp 66–75 Marshall T (1996) The evolution of restorative justice in Britain. Eur J Crim Policy Res 4(4):21–43 McCold P, Wachtel B (2002) Restorative justice theory validation. In: Weiterkamp et al (eds) Restorative justice: theoretical foundations. Willan Publishing, Devon, pp 110–142 Ministerio del Interior (2016) 2016 Datos nacionales completos. Report, Ministerio del Interior, Uruguay Olásolo H, Galain P (2018) Los desafíos del Derecho internacional penal ante su encrucijada actual: Atención especial a los casos de Argentina, Colombia, España, México y Uruguay. Tirant lo Blanch, Valencia Raina S, Kumar R (2017) A justice that heals: restorative justice from an Indian perspective. In: Thila- garaj et  al (eds) Restorative justice in India. Traditional practice and contemporary applications. Springer, Cham, pp 97–118 Reggio F (2010) Giustizia dialogica. Luci e ombre della restorative justice. Franco Angeli, Milano Seelmann K (2017) Verzicht auf Strafe? In: Saliger F (ed), Rechtsstaatliches Strafrecht. Festschrift für Ulfrid Neumann zum 70. Geburtstag, Heidelberg: Müller, pp 715–724 Sherman LW, Strang H (2007) Restorative justice: the evidence. The Smith Institute, London Sherman LW, Strang H (2010) Restorative justice as a psychological treatment: healing victims and reintegrating offenders. In: Towl G, Crichton D (eds) Handbook of forensic psychology. Elsevier, Amsterdam, pp 398–415 Sherman LW, Strang H, Angel C, Woods D, Barnes GC, Bennett S, Inkpen N (2005) Effects of face-to- face restorative justice on victims of crime in four randomized, controlled trials. J Exp Criminol 1(3):367–395 Streng F (1991) Strafrechtliche Sanktionen. Grundlagen und Anwendung. Kohlhammer, Stuttgart Transparency International (2017) Corruption Perceptions Index 2017. Available at https ://www.trans paren cy.org/news/featu re/corru ption _perce ption s_index _2017 (accessed 22 February 2018) Walgrave L (2001) On restoration and punishment: favourable similarities and fortunate differences. In: Morris H et al (eds) Restorative justice for juveniles: conferencing, mediation and circles. Hart Pub- lishing, Oxford, pp 17–37 World Prison Brief (2017) World Prison Brief data. Available at: http://www.priso nstud ies.org/world -priso n-brief -data (accessed 28 December 2017) Zehr H (2004) El pequeño libro de la justicia restaurativa. United States: Good Books. https://www.transparency.org/news/feature/corruption_perceptions_index_2017 https://www.transparency.org/news/feature/corruption_perceptions_index_2017 http://www.prisonstudies.org/world-prison-brief-data http://www.prisonstudies.org/world-prison-brief-data Restorative Justice in Uruguay: A Change of Lenses in a Reform of Criminal Justice? Abstract 1 Introduction 2 What is Restorative Justice? 3 Background 4 Restorative Justice in Uruguay 5 Restorative Justice in the New Uruguayan Criminal Procedure Code 6 Implementation and Preliminary Results 7 Discussion and Conclusions Acknowledgements References work_6ap25w4if5gg7p3l6ddfzha4ye ---- Ethics in Science and Environmental Politics 2002:65 ETHICS IN SCIENCE AND ENVIRONMENTAL POLITICS ESEP 2002, 65 –74 Published September 26 As environmental pressures on our planet continue to increase, there is a new urgency to find ways for- ward in making practical decisions. The difficulty in making such decisions is well known, given the diver- sity of interests and conflicting assessment of priorities in each case (Huxham & Sumner 2000: ix –xi). There are a number of possible underlying causes of these difficulties. In general, there has been a bias towards constructing the framework of decision-making in terms of specific cases, judged in terms of the relative risk or benefit of a particular action(s).1 A case-by-case pragmatic approach certainly yields results that are specific for the issue in hand, but is not the only way of describing ethical choice. I have suggested that in the particular situation of GMOs such a framing assumes a consequentialist approach to ethics that is not neces- sarily sufficient, given that risks are in many cases not readily quantified and the benefits more often than not directed to a particular group or community (Deane- Drummond 2001:119–28).2 If environmental risks are unclear, such as is often the case with genetically mod- ified (GM) crops, then decisions will either take place on the basis of supposed benefits, highlighted as gen- eral advantages by a particular interest group, or the precautionary principle will be invoked in order to delay action until such time as the risks are quantified. The precautionary principle is sometimes defined as ‘a strategy for dealing with environmental risk and uncertainty, which guides us to act cautiously and embark on a systematic programme of research to improve our understanding of the costs and benefits of particular actions’ (BMA 1999:17). There are a number of difficulties associated with this type of precautionary approach (Merritt & Jones 2000:84–87). In the first place there are different assessments as to the degree of environmental risk in defining when the precaution- ary principle will take effect. Secondly, the extent of environmental risk is itself highly contested (Lash et al. 1996). Of course there are some who interpret the pre- cautionary principle as the basis for inaction unless positive damage is proven not to be the case. Donald © Inter-Research 2002 · www.int-res.com *E-mail: c.deane-drummond@chester.ac.uk Wisdom with justice Celia Deane-Drummond* Department of Theology and Religious Studies, Chester College, Parkgate Road, Chester CH1 4BJ, United Kingdom ABSTRACT: This paper explores the way we make environmental decisions, especially in the context of heavily contested issues such as GMOs. It suggests that as well as attention to particular conse- quences of action, due consideration needs to be given to the motivation and attitudes of the agents concerned, in other words, to virtue ethics. The values behind environmental decision-making are predicated on religious as well as philosophical assumptions. I argue that not only is it important to identify religious mandates for environmental action through models such as that of kinship, but also that exploring the wisdom tradition from a Christian perspective can serve to clarify ways forward where decision making is difficult. In the Christian community itself a recovery of wisdom and justice as virtues can serve to raise the importance of environmental concern, since it is rooted in an under- standing of God as creator and the idea of natural law. The concept of justice complements that of wisdom in that it facilitates an objective stance according to certain principles of equity. Resale or republication not permitted without written consent of the publisher 1 I am using the term ‘risk’ in a traditional, rationalist sense; though as Donald Bruce suggests, there have been moves away from this definition in more recent discussions. See Bruce (2001). 2 I am not implying that consequences should never be taken into account, rather than viewing the problem just in terms of consequences alone may miss out other aspects of ethical insight that need to be taken into account. ESEP 2002, 65–74 Bruce has discussed the competing visions of precau- tion (Bruce 2001). The language of precaution, rather like that of sustainability, can be filled out with differ- ent contents depending on the players involved. Such a discovery implies that we need to look behind the language to the motivation of those who are using such language. This is the province of virtue ethics. I hope to show that one way of filling out what a virtue ethic might look like from a Christian perspective draws on a rediscovery of the importance of wisdom. Wisdom in addition includes the idea of prudence, or practical wisdom, which in its turn includes the concept of pre- caution. Precaution thus becomes both situated and critiqued in the context of a wider Christian vision of reality. The philosopher Mary Midgley has also identified another problem when it comes to making decisions about the environment. She suggests that even if the risks are well known, inaction will still follow if the imagination is not sufficiently engaged. In other words, bald scientific facts about the perilous state of the planet are insufficient to motivate action or decision- making in its favour (Midgley 2001:188). While she sees that there are signs that people do care about the earth, the reason for this is not so much the threat of environmental collapse, as a renewed sense that we are part of the earth and have evolved from it. Midgley believes that Gaian thinking can serve to challenge acute individualism and anthropocentrism, which she identifies as the heart of the problem (Midgley 2001: 171–174). Gaian thinking is certainly suggestive of a more holistic understanding of reality. However, as I have argued elsewhere, there are theological and eth- ical problems associated with a Gaian approach to the world (Deane-Drummond 2001: 165–183). For exam- ple, in its more idealistic forms, Gaia seems not only to equalise the place of humanity in relation to other spe- cies, but also to put bacteria and blue green algae at the top of the pyramid. Furthermore, if Gaia is held to be a stabilising global system, it could be used to sup- port environmental abuse, rather than the opposite. I suggest that Midgley is, nonetheless, correct in searching for alternative ways of approaching the way we think about the earth and identifying underlying values that are behind our decision-making. A com- mon Christian response to these difficulties has been to advocate the ideal of stewardship (Berry 2000: 25). While this can take us some way in making responsible decisions, the will to change remains largely untouched through this motif alone. Furthermore, stewardship often implies management of the planet, which in itself can be suggestive of a somewhat anthropocentric epistemology. While it is preferable to other biblical motifs such as the idea of kingship, it still tends to be hierarchical in its assumption that nature is somehow ‘below’ the order of humankind, human are ‘stewards’ over against the natural world. From a his- torical perspective the interpretation of the notion of stewardship is problematic, associated with ideas about dominion and dreams about repairing the nat- ural world through human ingenuity (Bauckham 2000: 100–102). A third alternative is that of kinship, devel- oping the notion that all creatures are in some sense part of who we are as human beings. Such a view is not only consistent with evolutionary science, it also artic- ulates an important biblical principle, namely that the creatures of the earth, including humans, give glory to God, rather than human beings alone (Bauckham 2002). In this paper I suggest that one way to develop an ethic towards the natural world that highlights the notion of kinship is through a recovery of the idea of wisdom. Such a recovery has a number of advantages. Firstly, it challenges the idea that science is the only way of knowing, instead wisdom invites a broader frame of reference compared with the fragmented problem solving approach characteristic of much of modern science (Deane-Drummond 2000:5–14). In the second place it connects with the philosophical trend in ethics that focuses on agents and attitudes rather than actions, known as virtue ethics. In the third place wisdom draws on ancient theological traditions and resonates with theological imagination. As such it can offer a vision that serves to inspire appropriate action. In the fourth place wisdom has ethical outcomes through its association with the cardinal virtues of practical wisdom or prudence, justice, temperance and fortitude. In this paper I focus specifically on the 2 virtues of prudence and justice and how they might be expressed in practice, as they seem to me to be of par- ticular relevance to environmental decision-making. The special attention to consequentialism in environ- mental decision-making may seem somewhat surpris- ing given the strong move in contemporary philosophy to recover an alternative approach to ethics that stresses moral character, namely virtue ethics (Crisp & Slote 1998, Hursthouse 1999). On the other hand, a purely deontological approach that frames particular issues from theological norms may seem out of touch with secular ethical debates (Deane-Drummond et al. 2001:35–36). Virtue ethics, by focusing on the agent, rather than just the possible outcomes of specific ethi- cal dilemmas in isolation, encourages ongoing moral attention that serves not only to sustain human resilience in times when decision making is difficult, but also to challenge all parties involved to re-examine their attitudes. Virtue ethics is characterised by being agent centred, rather than act centred, putting empha- sis on goodness, rather than rights, duties or obliga- tions, even positively rejecting the idea that ethics can 66 Deane-Drummond: Wisdom with justice be codified in rules. Yet this does not mean that virtue ethics is not interested in particular actions, or for that matter the consequences of those actions. Rather, the fundamental ethical question of what I should do is expanded into related questions about who I am, who I should become and how I should get there (Keenan 1998: 84). THEOLOGICAL WISDOM What is meant by theological wisdom?3 Wisdom, by definition, is hard to define with any precision, as she appears in various guises in scriptural and traditional texts. Nonetheless, even the early 17th century natural scientists, such as John Ray, found the motif of wisdom expressive of the way they hoped to discover traces of God in the natural world (Ray 1977). Ray was reluctant to attribute more to wisdom than a trace or reflection of the mind of God in creation. Other theologians, writing from an Eastern Orthodox perspective, have devel- oped a Sophiology that places Wisdom integral to the being of God.4 It seems fair to suggest that scriptural texts point in this direction. In the Old Testament book of Proverbs, for example, Wisdom is personified as the one who works alongside God in the creation of the world.5 Wisdom, according to the book of Wisdom, is ‘intelli- gent, holy, unique, manifold, subtle, active, incisive, unsullied, lucid, invulnerable, benevolent, sharp, irre- sistible, beneficient, loving to man, steadfast, depend- able, unperturbed, almighty, all-surveying’ (Wisdom 7:22–23). It could even be said that some wisdom books, such as the book of Ecclesiastes, echo to some extent the approach adopted by contemporary philoso- phers advocating virtue ethics (Christianson 2002). Wisdom in the Old Testament is also something that is learnt in the human community, through experience in practical decision-making in family life, education and observation of the natural world. What are the possible ways to find wisdom? The book of Proverbs invites his readers to ‘Go to the ant, you sluggard, See its ways and be wise’ (Proverbs 6:7). The seeing is not so much simple observation of information about the ants, as perceiving the inner distinctive core of what it is to be an ant (Habel 2002). In other places in wisdom litera- ture the word ‘to discern’ (bin) is used, often following the act of seeing, to describe the process of becoming wise. Hence discernment is integral to what it means to gain wisdom. Discernment considers a range of options, but ultimately lights on ‘the way’, understood not just as the alternative between 2 paths, but also as the inner driving characteristic of something (Habel 2002). This, it seems to me, is particularly important as it locates discernment as that which correctly identifies the inner core of something, that itself is expressive of wisdom. Significantly, in the book of Job 28 the char- acteristic of finding wisdom also applies to God, as God ‘sees’ the different components of creation (Habel 2002). On this basis it is possible that Proverbs 8:22 means not that God created wisdom, but the more common understanding of the word qana, namely God acquired wisdom. This reinforces the suggestion that I have made elsewhere that an essential characteristic of God is that of wisdom (Deane-Drummond 2000: 131–137). Moreover, there appears to be a dialectical relationship between God and the world in the cre- ative process. God creates through wisdom, but God discovers wisdom in its turn in the created order. This does not preclude the primary focus of the Christian tradition on God relating to the world through over- flowing love. Rather, creation is in love, but through wisdom. This sapiential understanding of God’s rela- tionship to the world has common ground with some other religious traditions and serves to challenge the individualistic way we think about ourselves and in its place situate humanity in the wider cosmic community of life (Nasr 1996: 205). 6 The Christian tradition, nonetheless, develops this perennial philosophy in a way that is distinct, namely through the notion of the wisdom of the cross (Deane- Drummond 2000: 52–59). The cross is proclaimed as the ultimate expression of the wisdom of God (1. Cor. 1.8–2.5). This aspect of wisdom might come as some- thing of a shock, yet it serves as a reminder of the suf- fering and cruelty evident in the natural world and in human relationships. The wisdom of the cross announces the fact that such suffering is not outside the concern of God who is in Christ, rather the cruci- fied one takes on such suffering in solidarity with the earth. The savage loss of species could be said to be a loss in God, for it is a loss in abundance of relationships (Larkin 2002). Nonetheless, for the Christian tradition the cross is not the last word, for its consideration is coloured by hope in the resurrection. John’s Gospel 67 3 I have discussed this idea in detail previously in Deane- Drummond 2000 4 Sergii Bulgakov is a good example, though it should be noted that his views on wisdom have been criticised by other orthodox scholars, such as Vladimir Lossky (For discussion see Deane-Drummond 2000: 78– 92) 5 The developing interest in wisdom literature among Old Testament scholars bespeaks of a relative neglect of this tra- dition, see Deane-Drummond 2000: 15–22 6 Nasr criticises the West for its focus on environmental ethics; for him a religious understanding of the order of nature needs to have a higher priority. I suggest that a shift in un- derstanding of ordering is commensurate with a new ethical approach ESEP 2002, 65–74 speaks of the Logos acting in the world in terms that resemble very closely the way Wisdom is spoken about in the Old Testament (Deane-Drummond 2003). Hence Christ as Logos is identified with Wisdom or Sophia. Yet for John the cross is also the cross of Glory, for it points to a future in which all creation will be redeemed. The message of wisdom is, then, ultimately a hopeful one, even if it resists turning away from the challenge of creaturely suffering. A RECOVERY OF A WISDOM ETHIC While there are a variety of ways of thinking about wisdom from a Christian perspective, I have argued elsewhere that a wisdom ethic drawing on the works of Thomas Aquinas gives significant insights about the way to approach the natural world (Deane-Drummond 2000:99–107, 2002). Wisdom as theological wisdom needs to be set in the context of the 3 theological virtues of faith, hope and charity. (1 Cor. 13). Wisdom is learned, but it is also a gift from God. As gift it is given by grace, rather than through rigid adherence to the law, even though it is not separate from law. Aquinas describes the 7 gifts of the Holy Spirit as wisdom, understanding, counsel, fortitude, knowledge, piety and fear of the Lord.7 In as much as it can be learned, it can be shared by all those of good will, whether Chris- tian or not. In this sense it is aligned with the idea of natural law. Yet divine Wisdom also finds expression in the eternal or divine law, which for Christians is expressed in obedience to the demands of the Gospel (Eph. 1. 8–10). Hence a measure of whether an action is wise or not is in relationship to this divine law, a point made repeatedly by Aquinas in his Summa The- ologiae (Cessario 2001:58-59).8 For Aquinas wisdom is one of the 3 intellectual virtues of speculative reason, the others being understanding, or grasping first prin- ciples and scientia, which denotes the comprehension of the causes of things and the relationship between them. In other words wisdom is the understanding of the fundamental causes of everything and their rela- tionship to everything else. In Aquinas wisdom is expressed theologically, for God is the ultimate cause of all that exists in virtue of the fact that God is creator. Human wisdom is a virtue directed towards the Wis- dom of God, for while wisdom can be learned it cannot be grasped or used for human aggrandisement (Proverbs 16). In the fullest sense human wisdom is only possible through the gift of the Holy Spirit by the grace of God. The Christian vocation includes develop- ing the virtue of wisdom, seeking her through obedi- ence to God’s covenant laws as well as acquiring her through education and family life. Wisdom is closely related to one of the intellectual virtues of practical reason, namely prudence, also termed practical wisdom. Practical wisdom is particu- larly significant for ethics, since it sets the way individ- ual virtues must be expressed in particular circum- stances. Developing prudence is not just about one’s inner attitude, though it includes this, but it is also about how this attitude is expressed in action.9 For example, practical wisdom comes into play in discern- ing what is the most appropriate way of acting in given circumstances. Virtuous behaviour may, in some cir- cumstances, be related to the means of attaining a par- ticular goal. For example, genetically engineering seed so that it is sterile in order to force farmers to buy new seed every year could be seen as an inappropriate means in order to attain the goal of maximum profits. The goal itself may also be challenged where it eclipses other goals such as respect for the needs of the local community. In this case a form of ‘prudence’ would have led to the decision that sterile seed is the best way of attaining the goal, but because the goal is faulty, this leads to what Aquinas describes as ‘sham prudence’. Indeed, for the biblical writers discernment and wisdom are intimately linked with the fear of the Lord (Proverbs 1.7, 2.5, 9.10 etc.). Hence, forms of dis- cernment that act against the needs of the community amount to folly. Perhaps more accurately we could say that the goal is a partial good, for it benefits relatively few people. Hence, a virtue ethic orientated around wisdom includes the idea of consequences, but it is in relationship to orientation towards the Good, under- stood in terms of that which is in accordance with covenant law. Aquinas also used the term ‘incomplete prudence’ to indicate that the good is narrowed to par- ticular individuals. These distorted forms of practical wisdom are worth bearing in mind, since from the per- spective of, for example, a biotechnology company an action could look like it is entirely prudent. However, once the wider needs of the community are taken into account, such formulation of practical wisdom is shown to be incomplete. In this scenario practical wisdom 68 7 The traditional formulation takes its bearings from the virtues possessed by the coming Messiah, as described by Isaiah 11:1–2, and taken up in early Christian traditions as corresponding to the gifts of the Spirit. (Cessario 2001: 205 –12) 8 In the light of this it might seem surprising that some moral philosophers have tended to abstract the idea of natural law from Aquinas, and ignored its link with covenant relation- ships. For discussion see Deane-Drummond 2002 9 Mary Midgley has criticised the effectiveness of prudence for motivating environmental decision-making. However, her understanding of prudence is one that relates simply to rational causes and individual self-interest, rather than be- ing situated in a broader theological understanding of wis- dom in the manner I am suggesting here (Midgley 2001:188) Deane-Drummond: Wisdom with justice relates strongly to justice, which I will discuss further below. However, virtues are more subtle in that expressing a particular virtue cannot necessarily always be described through means and ends type of analysis. What would count as behaving virtuously in the con- text of the practice of science and technology? While the goals of environmental decision-making and the means of attaining such goals may come under scrutiny through prudential considerations, the humil- ity to accept that the public may have important insights into social issues, the courage to challenge developments in those cases where the opinion of local farming communities have not been taken into account, actions such as these are not readily analysed simply in terms of means and ends. Practical wisdom includes a number of characteris- tics that are worth pondering in the present context. Aquinas draws on 5 areas related to knowing, namely memory, reason, understanding, aptness to being taught and ingenuity (Aquinas 1974: 55).10 Clearly rea- son, understanding and ingenuity all come into play in developing scientific methods that are sensitive to environmental concerns. Yet these characteristics alone are not sufficient for practical wisdom, since it includes memory as well. The ability to remember is associated with appreciation of history and tradition. The memory is used in a selective way in devising new technologies. Historically biotechnology has emerged as one more example of the way humankind engages with the natural world. However, it cannot simply be isolated from the social context of the culture of mod- ern industrial farming (Northcott 2002). While it may not be possible to return to earlier idealised communi- ties, in the way that Northcott seems to suggest, a deeper memory of what it means for humanity to be in relationship with the land would shift what is envis- aged in terms of practical wisdom. Aquinas identifies 3 areas of practical wisdom related to doing, namely foresight, circumspection and caution, or avoiding obstacles (Aquinas 1974: 55–57). 11 Foresight means the ability to be free from particular biases and to discern how far the intended aim matches the overall goal of human life understood as ultimate goodness. Where these goals are narrowly portrayed in terms of the particular products of tech- nology, then foresight is distorted. For example, does the introduction of vital vitamins to rice and other sta- ple crops grown in the poorer nations of the world even begin to solve the problem of nutrition in these nations? A technological fix can only be a temporary and even partial solution; for it ignores the fact that world hunger is more often than not the result of eco- nomic and social problems.12 Even expecting multina- tional companies to solve the world food crisis is a fail- ure of foresight, for it assumes that they will behave altruistically rather than be driven by market forces (Stewart 2002). Circumspection is the ability to attend to circumstances, and involves a clear perception of reality. For example, the possible ecological damage associated with genetically modified crops has not so far been adequately researched, since ‘we do not have an adequate ecological understanding of the complex interactions engendered by releasing GMOs even into semi-natural ecosystems’ (Walton 2000: 15).13 Finally, prudence also expresses caution, or avoiding obsta- cles. There are numerous examples in genetic technol- ogy where there are clear risks involved either to human health or the environment. Where these risks are exaggerated, this amounts to a distortion of practi- cal wisdom. For example, the research published by Dr Arpad Pusztai claiming that a modified lectin gene causes adverse effects in rats was not subjected to nor- mal peer review and scrutiny prior to publication (Deane-Drummond 2001: 65). Despite this, campaign- ers and the media have used his work to make irre- sponsible claims that genetic modification causes seri- ous intestinal infection in rats, when in fact his research simply describes the structure of the small intestine (Dixon 2001:275). The precautionary principle is commonly adopted by committees adjudicating on whether or not to approve particular developments in GM research and associ- 69 10 While Aquinas takes this list from Aristotle, biblical wisdom also includes similar ideas of memory and aptness to being taught (Proverbs 3:1), reason and understanding (Proverbs 2:5, 18:15) and ingenuity (Proverbs 8:30) 12 Correcting one vitamin deficiency alone is likely to be of limited benefit because of the interaction between different vitamins and minerals needed for good health. While the researchers involved were in all probability well aware of this limitation, it is worth asking if the funding spent so far on such a development is really appropriate, given its lim- ited value. Shiva has suggested that red rice growing natu- rally has about ten times the concentration of vitamin A compared with the ‘golden rice’ modified by genetic engi- neering. (Shiva 2002). Public consultation is critical if such developments are not going to be perceived as yet another form of neo-colonialism, however good the intentions. The virtue of foresight can serve to encourage such a wider per- ception, rather than limiting the consideration to one of iso- lated problem solving 13 David Walton suggests, that if the funding was supported by the state then there might be greater public acceptance that ‘objectives were really feeding the hungry and not greater dividends, and that the control and oversight mech- anisms were robust enough to ensure that health and the environment would be protected as far as possible’, Walton 2000:15 11 These ideas are also found in instructions to those who wish to acquire wisdom in Proverbs, for circumspection, see Proverbs 14:8, for foresight and caution see Proverbs 14:16, 22:3 ESEP 2002, 65–74 ated environmental decisions. In this scenario we are left with the alternatives to adopt or reject the precau- tionary principle, along with difficulties of its defini- tion. Instead, I suggest that precaution needs to be just one factor set in a much wider frame of practical wis- dom, including the various elements indicated above. The lack of trust of governments on the part of the pub- lic is suggestive of alternative ways of framing deci- sion-making that takes this suspicion into account (Deane-Drummond et al. 2001:23 –24). Wisdom, as that which delves behind the attitudes of those making the decisions, is one possible step in the rebuilding of rela- tionships that is so vitally needed. THE SIGNIFICANCE OF JUSTICE AS VIRTUE I indicated earlier that virtue of justice is an appro- priate companion to prudence and wisdom in framing appropriate ethical action. The ancient sages were well aware of the link between justice and wisdom, indeed Proverbs personifies Lady Wisdom as one who ‘By me monarchs rule and princes issue just laws; by me rulers govern and the great impose justice on the world’ (Proverbs 8.16–17). In the monarchical society of the time, kingship, wisdom and justice were inter- twined. A more appropriate framework for today is kinship, rather than kingship, but this shift need not deny the basic principle of linking justice and wisdom. Virtue ethicists have tended to associate justice with Kantian ethics, but for Aquinas justice is also a virtue to be acquired, alongside prudence or practical wis- dom.14 Indeed when justice is defined in association with rights, it no longer makes logical sense to speak of justice towards future generations that is the premise of much environmental concern (Beckerman & Pasek 2001:11–45). This means that additional ethical resources are required in order to elucidate obliga- tions, and Beckerman & Pasek are driven to hint at the possibility of virtue theory making a contribution in this respect. However it is not filled out in any detail and they seem to assume that justice is not a virtue (Beckerman & Pasek 2001:24–25). Of course, unlike the other virtues, justice also has an objective basis through particular acts that could be characterised as just or not. In this sense justice moves away from virtue ethics sensus strictus in terms of agents and attitudes towards a more deontological position.15 In a similar way I indicated earlier that consequences are also taken into account in making prudential choices. This means that those following Kantian views can take into account some of the advantages gained through virtue ethics, so I suggest that it is possible to incorporate ideas about what counts as justice without losing the emphasis on the importance of the virtues. In a just order, each is given his or her due. This once again raises the priority of consideration of the needs of the poor as well as consideration of non-human creatures and the wider environment. Beckerman & Pasek pre- dict that there will be continuing economic growth and this will have a trickle down effect on alleviation of basic environmental problems and poverty, though basic human rights remain untouched by economic trends (2001:89–106). Yet their assumption that acute problems associated with environment and poverty will become progressively ameliorated amounts to eco- nomic reductionism based on economic forecasts. In addition, they seem to assume that the demands of the environment and those of the poor are in some sense in competition for the same economic resources, while recognising that they do at times intersect. Clearly, the means of deciding which environmental problem takes priority over which particular demand from a human community is critical, but this is not discussed. It is one of the reasons why I suggest that justice needs to be aligned with practical wisdom, understood as discern- ment: once justice is considered to be a virtue it no longer has to be associated so closely with the lan- guage of rights. The human virtue of justice, under- stood in terms of human obligations, can take into account the importance of the non-human species as part of the overall ecological community. What are the duties in relation to the ‘others’ in the community of life? Certainly, there may be legally binding actions that have to be undertaken, that are more based on particular objective rules, but also morally binding ones as well that are more closely aligned with attitudes of the agents. Even within the moral sphere it is possible to distinguish that which is dishonourable as opposed to that which is unseemly. The distinction between these various forms of justice as virtue can be illustrated as follows. Ten thousand hectares of genetically engineered cotton have been found growing in India in the Western state of Gujarat (Jayaraman 2001: 555). The cotton had been geneti- cally engineered to resist the bollworm using a gene from Bacillus thuringiensis. This gene (Bt) acts like an insecticide in the plants, and they are no longer 70 14 Onora O’Neill combines a Kantian approach with virtue ethics, see O’Neill 1996 15 It could be argued that wisdom also, as a theological cate- gory, moves away from virtue ethics in the manner under- stood by most philosophers. However, my intention is not to simply imitate virtue ethics, but to draw on these insights and incorporate them into a theocentric ethic of wisdom. Such a theocentric ethic is less alienating compared with other deontological theological positions, as it resonates with the language of virtues and orientates discussion around agents first, prior to consideration of particular theo- logical principles Deane-Drummond: Wisdom with justice infected. The farmers purchased their seed from Navb- harat, a small company which originally purchased seed from Maharashtra Hybrid Seeds Company, Mahyco. Monsato have a 26 % stake in the latter com- pany and the seed is freely available for purchase in the USA. The row exploded because Monsanto discov- ered Bt cotton on farms on the Western state of Gujarat and they had not been paid for the patents. Navbharat could argue that it lacked the technology to detect transgenic strains. From a legal perspective the action of Navbharat is against the law, breaking the legal requirement to pay dividends for patents on particular ‘inventions’, in this case GM cotton. It is not clear if Monsato had been granted an Indian patent on Bt cot- ton as the work with Mahyco was still at the field trial stage. Mahyco had spent US$8 million on preparing to commercialise Bt cotton for the Indian market. In terms of business ethics Mahyco/Monsato did have their par- ticular ‘rights’ violated according to patent law. It is also worth asking how far the Indian regulatory system is able to ensure that the patent can be carried out in terms of monitoring the seed. Perhaps the Indian authorities were imprudent in granting a patent in the first place. From the perspective of justice in the widest sense it is possible to ask whether the multinational giant Monsanto is morally justified in making such demands for patent payments where it is doubtful if India would ever have the resources for adequate monitoring. The practice of Western companies indulging in ‘gene piracy’ (i.e. the lifting of genetic resources from poorer nations and then imposing a patent on them), as well as the introduction of particular genetic traits such as ‘terminator genes’, serve to break down the trust between larger companies and our neighbours in the Southern nations of the world (Bruce & Horrocks 2002: 132–134).16 Both Monsanto’s attitude and their action could be said to be dishonourable in making demands for payments for patents from nations that can ill afford to do so. In addition, the imposition of patent law implies that frameworks adequate for an industrialised Western nation cannot be applied in a crude way to that of a poorer ‘developing’ community. It raises wider questions about the whole system of patenting as applied on an international level. Moreover what would be the social consequences for subsistent farm- ers growing traditional crops if agricultural practice shifted significantly towards commercial GMOs? The motivation of Monsanto in developing GM cotton for the Indian market was clearly commercial. If the offi- cials on either side behaved in such as way as to express hostility or anger, then such an attitude could be said to be unseemly. Justice is violated in this case because it serves to break down relationships in a com- munity. All acts of virtue relate in one sense or another to justice, hence Aquinas refers to justice as the ‘most perfect virtue’. 17 Developing cash crops specifically for use in the Indian subcontinent could be said to be an example of ecological injustice. The chairman of an Indian department of biotechnology committee has asked whether ‘this is a foretaste of a frightening situ- ation where transgenics will be out of control and all over the place’. 18 Yet the ‘solution’ to this biotechno- logical problem is to press for Rs100 million to be spent on national laboratories to monitor GMOs. Given the reality of the shortage of funds for other work, is this a just use of resources? The above example suggests that an act of justice can be judged, as it were, from the outside in an objec- tive way. This makes justice different from the other virtues such as temperance or fortitude. Acts of justice are not necessarily affected by particular dispositions towards another; hence it is possible to act justly while not having an inner disposition towards justice. It may be that the Indian company mistakenly mixed up the seed used, but while this would be a legal injustice according to patent law, it would not render the com- pany unjust. However, the ideal of justice as virtue requires both an inner assent to justice as well as an external just action. Justice also reflects obligations to the community, hence in Aquinas’s scheme it is ranked higher than other virtues such as temperance or forti- tude that relate simply to inner dispositions. While justice as virtue is the starting point for effec- tive environmental decision-making, consideration of wider concerns of justice locates the virtue in the con- text of a particular way of thinking in an objective sense about just relationships. Aquinas divided the just ordering in community life to firstly that between indi- viduals, or commutative justice; secondly to that between the whole and the individual or distributive justice; and thirdly that between the individual and social whole or legal justice (Pieper 1966:70 –74). These distinctions follow from the fact that the kind of legal protection afforded by the state is different in kind to that which is due between individuals. The philosopher Josef Pieper criticises individualism in not taking sufficient account of the reality of the social whole in making just decisions (Pieper 1966:70–74). On the other hand, there is an opposite danger in col- lectivism, where no one individual enters a relation- ship in their own right. In this case no individual is given any right, and hence no due. The idea of justice 71 16 Vandana Shiva has called this kind of action ‘piracy’. See Shiva 1998, 2001 17 I am drawing on the somewhat neglected work of the Ro- man Catholic philosopher, Josef Pieper (1966) 18 Cited in Jayaraman 2001 ESEP 2002, 65–74 collapses. Some forms of deep ecology and Gaian thinking seem to lean far too heavily in this direction. Of course Aquinas’ scheme fails to take into account the corporate nature of contemporary existence in so far as today, legally speaking, multinational companies have rights. Hence particular companies have particu- lar responsibilities to act according to the law. Commutative justice is what is owed to a stranger and follows what is due according to particular con- tracts. For all intents and purposes commutative justice could be said to apply to biotechnological companies in relation to individuals and their claims for particular demands for what is due in their case. The relationship between parties needs to be one of mutual respect, rather than hostility, so that the task of commutative justice is: ‘to bring solace and order into the conflict of contending interests which by their nature are legitimate opposites and not easily reconcilable, to impose on them, as it were, a posterior order, is the office and task of commutative justice’ (Pieper 1966:79). In the case of GMOs the task of commutative justice would be to ensure that no damage exists to someone or their property as a result of the release of GMOs. However, where accidents happen, such as in the case of accidental contamination of organic farms during field trials of GMOs, then compensation would be required since some recompense needs to be made. Of course this presupposes that it is possible for GMO field trials to take place without any risk of contamina- tion. Given the close proximity of different farming practices in countries such as the UK, this may not be feasible. In this scenario, it might be possible to argue for ‘organic-free zones’ as well as ‘GM free zones’. The just person needs to recognise the wrong committed, admit to the injustice and endeavour to eradicate it. The problem in the case of organic farming is that both organic and non-organic farmers claim an equal right to practice farming according to particular principles, though an assessment of risk to organic farmers would seem to be prudent prior to approval of field trials. The case of multinationals also crosses into a second area of justice, namely distributive justice, since this describes the relationship between those who have power and those who are in some sense ‘delivered’ to this power. Since biotechnology is governed largely by the work of multinationals plus in some cases central government, the responsibility for just action becomes one of distributive justice. The difference is that whereas in the classic understanding of distributive justice, what belongs to an individual is a share in what belongs to everyone, for multinationals, apart from its relationship to its own employees or stake holders, the individual has no share or part in its activities, except in so far as the flourishing of the company boosts the overall economy of the state as a whole. Those who are guardians of the common weal calcu- late what is due to the individual in the case of distrib- utive justice. For state rendered compensation, partic- ular subjects of particular grievances are taken into account in a way that is not true of commutative jus- tice. Yet where those who are responsible do not exer- cise their powers justly, then injustice reigns. Where the law of the state restrains multinationals to act responsibly towards individuals and the environment, then one can expect some measure of justice to ensue. However, what happens in those situations where state law is less regulated such as the relative lack of regu- lations on the safe use of chemicals, fertilisers and also genetically modified crops in the poorer nations of the world? According to a recent report ‘developing coun- tries have less well developed regulatory structures and expertise to manage the introduction of GM crops appropriately’ (Nuffield Council on Bioethics 1999: 136). In this case justice relies on being exercised by the multinational companies towards strangers, in this case those living in such nations. The parties to the global convention on biodiversity (CBD) are trying to adopt a Biosafety Protocol. While this may act like ‘a first line of defence’ it relies on members being part of this wider global community. In these instances, inter- national bodies also contribute to the working out of justice. CONCLUSIONS In addition to social and political considerations, I have argued that in order to uncover the reasons behind difficulties in environmental decision making we need to explore human attitudes and motivation. One attitude of particular significance is that of wis- dom, for not only does it link with practical reason through prudence, but also from a theological perspec- tive it joins with an understanding of the relationship between God, humanity and the world. In other words wisdom invites a theocentric perspective on ethics that does not exclude secular ethical considerations, but encompasses and critiques different secular alterna- tives. Given that I have argued for a recovery of Aquinas’ way of approaching ethics, his views on prac- tical wisdom and justice as virtues are also of particu- lar importance. Prudence is the first of the cardinal virtues and serves to shape the way they develop. In other words, there can be no justice without prudence. Justice is situated in the context of right relationships between God and the created world understood in terms of covenant. The nature of the relationships themselves can be described theologically in terms of 72 Deane-Drummond: Wisdom with justice wisdom. How might this work out in practical decision- making? I suggest that those who are responsible for making decisions have a responsibility to examine closely the attitudes and motivation of all contesting parties. In terms of raising environmental awareness and concern, wisdom reminds us of the importance of the created order, the need to consider the beauty and intricacy of creation, and hence is aligned to other virtues such as wonder and humility. A virtue ethic ori- entated on wisdom challenges the sufficiency of conse- quential approaches, while including the prudential discernment of consequences as integral to what it means to have virtue. For Christian believers such scrutiny of attitudes becomes part and parcel of Chris- tian discipleship, since such decisions are consistent with what it means to inaugurate the reign of God and express God’s wisdom. The Christian vision includes one of kinship with creatures, so that all creatures are not simply for instrumental human use, but are given respect as those that embody, to some degree, the wis- dom of God. In discussing the merits or otherwise of biotechno- logical change, justice between individuals and corpo- rations is not simply definable in terms of breaking the law such as that covering patents, because there are moral aspects of justice that make particular attitudes and actions dishonourable. Yet justice requires pru- dential consideration of the alternatives before a claim can be made. In other words, the ability to see reality clearly — which is the province of practical wisdom - leads to actions that affect human relationships with each other — which is the province of justice. This paper has attempted to delineate some of the ways in which wisdom and justice as virtues could facilitate environmental decision-making. I have argued that wisdom is integral to an understanding of who God is and thus needs to be reflected in the way humanity relates to each other and to the natural world. The search for wisdom is always incomplete, for it involves the shared search of the wider community of the pub- lic including theologians and scientists. I suggest that it is in and through such collaboration that respect for God and for each other develops. Perhaps we can say that this developing respect is the beginning of wis- dom (Proverbs 1:1–7). LITERATURE CITED Aquinas T (1974) Summa Theologiae 2a2ae, Vol 36, Pru- dence, Qu. 48 Parts of Prudence, translated by T Gilby. Blackfriars, London Bauckham R (2000) Stewardship and relationship. In: Berry RJ (ed) The care of Creation. IVP, Leicester, p 99 –106 Bauckham R (2002) Voicing Creation’s praise. Ecotheology 7.1:45 – 59 Beckerman W, Pasek J (2001) Justice, posterity and the envi- ronment. Oxford University Press, Oxford. Berry RJ (ed) (2000) The care of Creation: focusing concern and action. IVP, Leicester: BMA (1999) The impact of genetic modification on agricul- ture, food and health: an interim statement. British Med- ical Association, London Bruce D (2001) How far should we take the precautionary principle? Paper delivered to the British Ecology Society and the Linnean Society, April 26th 2001, Burlington House, London Bruce D, Horrocks D (eds) (2001) Modifying Creation? GM crops and foods: a Christian perspective. Evangelical Alliance Policy Commission, London Cessario R (2001) Introduction to moral theology. The Catholic University of America Press, Washington, DC Christianson E (2002) The ethics of narrative wisdom: a test case. In: Brown W (ed) The character of Scripture: moral formation, identity, and ethics in the Bible. Eerdmans, New York (in press) Crisp R, Slote M (1998) Virtue ethics. Oxford University Press, Oxford Deane-Drummond C (2000) Creation through wisdom: theol- ogy and the new biology. T & T Clark, Edinburgh Deane-Drummond C (2001) Biology and theology today: exploring the boundaries. SCM Press, London Deane-Drummond C (2002) Aquinas, wisdom ethics and the new genetics. In: Deane-Drummond C, Szerszynski B (eds) Re-ordering nature: theology, society and the new genetics. T & T Clark/Continuum, Edinburgh (in press) Deane-Drummond C (2003 The Logos as Wisdom: a starting point for a Sophianic theology of Creation. In: Clayton P, Peacocke A (eds) In whom we live and move and have our being: reflections on panentheism in a scientific age. Eerdmans, New York (in press) Deane-Drummond C, Szerszynski B, Grove-White R (2001) Genetically modified theology. Studies in Christian Ethics (14):25– 41 Dixon B (2001) Transgenic ills and otherwise: Review of Redesigning Life? In: Toker B (ed) The worldwide chal- lenge to genetic engineering, Nature 412:275 Jayaraman K.S (2001) Illicit cotton sparks corporate fury. Nature 413:555 Habel, N (2002) The Book of Job: Suffering and cognition in context, Paper delivered to the colloquium of the Royal Netherlands Academy of Arts and Sciences, April 22 –23 2002 Hursthouse R (1999) On virtue ethics. Oxford University Press, Oxford Huxham M, Sumner D (eds) (2000) Science and environmen- tal decision making. Prentice Hall/Pearson Education, Edinburgh Johnson E (1992) She who is: the mystery of god in feminist theological Discourse. Crossroad, New York Keenan J (1998) Virtue Ethics. In: Hoose B (ed) Christian ethics: an introduction. Cassell, London, p 84 –94 Larkin L (2002) Face-to-face with Limobius mixtus, Ecotheol- ogy, 7.1:30 – 44 Lash S, Bronislaw S, Wynne B (1996) Risk, environment and modernity: towards a new ecology. Sage, London Merritt JQ, Jones PC (2000) Science and environmental deci- sion-making: The social context. In: Huxham M, Sumner D (eds) Science and environmental decision making. Prentice Hall/Pearson Education, Edinburgh, p 63-93 Midgley M (2001) Science and poetry. Routledge, London Nasr S (1996) Religion and the order of nature. Oxford Uni- versity Press, Oxford 73 ESEP 2002, 65–74 Northcott M (2002) Behold I have set the land before you. (Deut. 1.8): Christian Ethics, GM foods and the culture of modern farming. In: Deane-Drummond C, Szerszynski B (eds) Re-ordering nature: theology, society and the new genetics. T & T Clark/Continuum, Edinburgh (in press) Nuffield Council on Bioethics (1999) Genetically modified crops: the ethical and social issues. Nuffield, London O’Neill O (1996) Towards justice and virtue: a constructive account of practical reasoning. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Pieper J (1966). The four cardinal virtues. University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame Ray J (1691/1977) The wisdom of God manifested in the works of creation. Arno Press, New York Shiva V (1998). Biopiracy. Green Books, London Shiva V (2001) Stolen Harvest: The hijacking of the global food supply. Zed Books, London Shiva V (2002) Opening plenary. Workshop on life on a threatened planet: genetic controversy and environmental ethics, June 4, 2002, Centre for Theology and the Natural Sciences, University of Berkeley, California, USA Stewart J (2002) Reordering means and ends: Ellul and the New Genetics. In: Deane-Drummond C, Szerszynski B (eds) Re-ordering nature: theology, society and the new genetics. T & T Clark/Continuum, Edinburgh (in press) Walton D (2000) Genetically modified futures? Brit Ecol Soc Bull 31(2):14 –16 74 Editorial responsibility: R.J. (Sam) Berry, London, United Kingdom Submitted: September 4, 2002; Accepted: September 7, 2002 Proofs received from author(s): September 23, 2002 Published on the web: September 26, 2002 work_6jekflb7tne2tjb6etuv2rfz4m ---- [PDF] Shared and Configural Justice: A Social Network Model of Justice in Teams | Semantic Scholar Skip to search formSkip to main content> Semantic Scholar's Logo Search Sign InCreate Free Account You are currently offline. Some features of the site may not work correctly. DOI:10.5465/AMR.2005.17293715 Corpus ID: 37800739Shared and Configural Justice: A Social Network Model of Justice in Teams @article{Roberson2005SharedAC, title={Shared and Configural Justice: A Social Network Model of Justice in Teams}, author={Quinetta Roberson and J. Colquitt}, journal={Academy of Management Review}, year={2005}, volume={30}, pages={595-607} } Quinetta Roberson, J. Colquitt Published 2005 Sociology Academy of Management Review We propose a model of justice in teams that articulates the social influence processes through which shared perceptions of justice emerge and that explores the subsequent effects on team effectiveness outcomes. We also consider barriers to the emergence of shared team justice and introduce configural forms of justice that may result. Theoretical and practical contributions of the model for understanding the meaning and operation of justice at the team level of analysis are discussed.  View via Publisher media.terry.uga.edu Save to Library Create Alert Cite Launch Research Feed Share This Paper 191 CitationsHighly Influential Citations 4 Background Citations 79 Methods Citations 5 Results Citations 4 View All Figures from this paper figure 1 figure 2 191 Citations Citation Type Citation Type All Types Cites Results Cites Methods Cites Background Has PDF Publication Type Author More Filters More Filters Filters Sort by Relevance Sort by Most Influenced Papers Sort by Citation Count Sort by Recency Justice in Self-Managing Teams: The Role of Social Networks in the Emergence of Procedural Justice Climates Quinetta Roberson, Ian O. Williamson Sociology 2012 68 Save Alert Research Feed Justice in teams : The activation and role of sensemaking in the emergence of justice climates Quinetta Roberson Psychology 2006 123 Save Alert Research Feed Examining JusticE from a social nEtwork PErsPEctivE Dan Brass Political Science 2008 7 Save Alert Research Feed A Multi-Level Analysis of Organizational Justice Climate, Structure, and Employee Mental Health† C. Spell, Todd Arnold Psychology 2007 148 Save Alert Research Feed Ethics, Values, and Organizational Justice: Individuals, Organizations, and Beyond Marshall Schminke, A. Arnaud, R. Taylor Sociology 2015 32 Save Alert Research Feed The Joint Effects of Justice Climate, Group Moral Identity, and Corporate Social Responsibility on the Prosocial and Deviant Behaviors of Groups Meghan A. Thornton, D. Rupp Psychology 2016 25 Save Alert Research Feed Chapter 10 The fairness of difference: How team composition affects the emergence of justice climates Quinetta Roberson, Ian O. Williamson Political Science 2010 1 Save Alert Research Feed Chapter 9 From justice events to justice climate: A multi-level temporal model of information aggregation and judgment D. Rupp, E. Paddock Political Science 2010 45 Save Alert Research Feed An employee-centered model of organizational justice and social responsibility: D. Rupp Psychology 2011 196 Save Alert Research Feed An employee-centered model of organizational justice and social responsibility Deborah E. Rupp 2011 2 View 2 excerpts, cites background Save Alert Research Feed ... 1 2 3 4 5 ... References SHOWING 1-10 OF 88 REFERENCES SORT BYRelevance Most Influenced Papers Recency A Case for Procedural Justice Climate: Development and Test of a Multilevel Model Stefanie E. Naumann, Nathan Bennett Psychology 2000 566 View 2 excerpts, references background Save Alert Research Feed Justice at the millennium: a meta-analytic review of 25 years of organizational justice research. J. Colquitt, D. E. Conlon, M. J. Wesson, C. O. Porter, K. Ng Psychology, Medicine The Journal of applied psychology 2001 4,523 PDF View 2 excerpts, references background Save Alert Research Feed JUSTICE IN TEAMS: ANTECEDENTS AND CONSEQUENCES OF PROCEDURAL JUSTICE CLIMATE J. Colquitt, R. Noe, C. L. Jackson Psychology 2002 613 View 1 excerpt Save Alert Research Feed A Multilevel Analysis of Procedural Justice Context K. W. Mossholder, Nathan Bennett, C. Martin Psychology 1998 280 Save Alert Research Feed Understanding Procedural Justice and Its Impact on Business Organizations M. A. Konovsky Psychology 2000 742 View 1 excerpt, references background Save Alert Research Feed RETALIATION IN THE WORKPLACE: THE ROLES OF DISTRIBUTIVE, PROCEDURAL, AND INTERACTIONAL JUSTICE D. Skarlicki, R. Folger Psychology 1997 1,906 PDF View 1 excerpt, references background Save Alert Research Feed Building Commitment, Attachment, and Trust in Strategic Decision-Making Teams: The Role of Procedural Justice M. Korsgaard, D. M. Schweiger, H. Sapienza Psychology 1995 952 View 1 excerpt, references background Save Alert Research Feed Understanding why the justice of group procedures matters: A test of the psychological dynamics of the group-value model. T. Tyler, P. Degoey, H. Smith Psychology 1996 766 Save Alert Research Feed Collective restraint in social dilemmas: Procedural justice and social identification effects on support for authorities. T. Tyler, P. Degoey Psychology 1995 493 View 1 excerpt, references background Save Alert Research Feed The Social Psychology of Procedural Justice E. Lind, T. Tyler Political Science 1988 5,207 View 2 excerpts, references background Save Alert Research Feed ... 1 2 3 4 5 ... Related Papers Abstract Figures 191 Citations 88 References Related Papers Stay Connected With Semantic Scholar Sign Up About Semantic Scholar Semantic Scholar is a free, AI-powered research tool for scientific literature, based at the Allen Institute for AI. Learn More → Resources DatasetsSupp.aiAPIOpen Corpus Organization About UsResearchPublishing PartnersData Partners   FAQContact Proudly built by AI2 with the help of our Collaborators Terms of Service•Privacy Policy The Allen Institute for AI By clicking accept or continuing to use the site, you agree to the terms outlined in our Privacy Policy, Terms of Service, and Dataset License ACCEPT & CONTINUE work_6l2trl7k65h2tdmmgmgpj26mgq ---- 1 23 Ethical Theory and Moral Practice An International Forum ISSN 1386-2820 Volume 15 Number 3 Ethic Theory Moral Prac (2012) 15:369-386 DOI 10.1007/s10677-011-9300-0 Burdened Societies and Transitional Justice Lisa L. Fuller 1 23 Your article is protected by copyright and all rights are held exclusively by Springer Science+Business Media B.V.. This e-offprint is for personal use only and shall not be self- archived in electronic repositories. If you wish to self-archive your work, please use the accepted author’s version for posting to your own website or your institution’s repository. You may further deposit the accepted author’s version on a funder’s repository at a funder’s request, provided it is not made publicly available until 12 months after publication. Burdened Societies and Transitional Justice Lisa L. Fuller Accepted: 12 June 2011 /Published online: 30 June 2011 # Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011 Abstract Following John Rawls, nonideal theory is typically divided into: (1) “partial- compliance theory” and (2) “transitional theory." The former is concerned with those circumstances in which individuals and political regimes do not fully comply with the requirements of justice, such as when people break the law or some individuals do not do their fair share within a distributive scheme. The latter is concerned with circumstances in which background institutions may be unjust or may not exist at all. This paper focuses on issues arising in transitional theory. In particular, I am concerned with what Rawls’ has called “burdened societies," that is, those societies that find themselves in unfavorable conditions, such that their historical, social or economic circumstances make it difficult to establish just institutions. The paper investigates exactly how such burdened societies should proceed towards a more just condition in an acceptable fashion. Rawls himself tells us very little, except to suggest that societies in this condition should look for policies and courses of action that are morally permissible, politically possible and likely to be effective. In this paper I first try to anticipate what a Rawlsian might say about the best way for burdened societies to handle transitional problems and so move towards the ideal of justice. Next, I construct a model of transitional justice for burdened societies. Ultimately, I argue for a model of transitional justice that makes use of a nonideal version of Rawls’ notion of the worst-off representative person. Keywords Burdened societies . Transitional theory. Nonideal theory. Development . Human rights 1 Introduction John Rawls famously divides political philosophy into ideal and nonideal theory. Ideal theory “assumes strict compliance and works out the principles that characterize a well- ordered society under favorable circumstances,” while nonideal theory “is worked out after Ethic Theory Moral Prac (2012) 15:369–386 DOI 10.1007/s10677-011-9300-0 L. L. Fuller (*) Department of Philosophy, University at Albany (SUNY), 1400 Washington Ave., Albany, NY 12222, USA e-mail: lfuller@albany.edu Author's personal copy a conception of [ideal] justice has been chosen,” and “asks how this long-term goal might be achieved, or worked toward, usually in gradual steps” (Rawls (1999a) p. 216, hereafter “TOJ”; Rawls (1999b) p. 89, hereafter “LP”.) He further divides nonideal theory into two kinds: (1) “partial-compliance theory” and (2) “transitional theory” (Rawls LP, pp. 5, 90). Partial-compliance theory is concerned with those circumstances in which individuals and political regimes do not fully comply with the requirements of (domestic or international) justice, such as when people break the law or when states engage in wars of aggression. Transitional theory is concerned with circumstances in which background institutions are unjust or do not exist at all, due to the natural limitations of agents, historical contingencies, or unfavorable conditions such as extreme poverty (Rawls TOJ, p. 216; LP p. 90). This paper focuses on issues arising in transitional theory. In particular, I am concerned with what Rawls’ has called “burdened societies,” that is, those generally peaceable societies that “lack the political and cultural traditions, the human capital and know-how, and often, the material and technological resources needed to be well-ordered” (Rawls LP, p. 106). Burdened societies find themselves in “historical, social or economic circumstances” that make it “difficult if not impossible” to establish just institutions.1 The purpose of this paper is to investigate how such burdened societies can reasonably proceed towards a more just condition. When facing problems in nonideal theory, Rawls suggests that we must look for “policies and courses of action that are morally permissible and politically possible as well as likely to be effective [emphasis added]” (Rawls LP, p. 89). However, he offers little insight into how societies might go about meeting these requirements. This is not surprising, since his general approach does not depart sufficiently from the ideal to make these issues especially salient. I intend to “take up where he left off” so to speak, that is, to construct a model of transitional justice for burdened societies. The paper has four main sections. First, I outline the “terrain” and methodology appropriate to nonideal theory as I conceive it. Next, I explain how burdened societies fit into Rawls’ overall project, and how they ought to be understood. Third, I try to anticipate what a Rawlsian might say about the best way for them to handle transitional problems and so move towards the ideal of justice. Finally, I argue for a model of transitional justice that makes use of a nonideal version of Rawls’ notion of the worst-off representative person. 2 Notes on Non-ideal Theory Recent work in nonideal theory contains persuasive arguments for expanding its scope beyond the original definition introduced by Rawls. In addition, much of this work has specified in some detail both the subject matter and methods suitable to nonideal theorizing. Rather than giving an exhaustive overview of these developments, in this section I simply aim to explain those features of nonideal theory that will be relevant to my later discussion. On the traditional picture, nonideal theory presupposes ideal theory. According to Rawls, “until the ideal is identified … nonideal theory lacks an objective, an aim, by reference to which its queries can be answered” (Rawls LP, p. 90). Further, existing arrangements are to be judged in light of our understanding of what is ideally just, and “held to be unjust to the extent that they depart from [the ideal] without sufficient reason” (Rawls TOJ, p. 216). Ideal 1 Rawls, LP, p. 5. I leave aside cases of total impossibility, since if there are no possible reforms that a burdened society could implement that would lead to a more just condition, then I have nothing to discuss. However, given the ability of societies to change, especially with the input and assistance of other societies, it seems likely that these cases will be very few. 370 L.L. Fuller Author's personal copy John Simmons points out that in Law of Peoples Rawls claims that ideal theory has two “parts” or “domains.” The first part of ideal theory “is an account of justice appropriate to liberal democratic societies,” that is, principles for a perfectly just society as laid out in a Theory of Justice. The other part “extends the same ideas to the international community, deriving principles for a ‘society of peoples’ … that can bring about and make stable (‘well-order’) a just international ‘society’” (Simmons (2010), p. 10). Simmons identifies two corresponding parts of nonideal theory—one addressing failures of domestic institutions to live up to the ideal of justice, and the other addressing failures of societies to live up to the requirements of ideal international justice. Finally, Simmons, like others, notes “that there is third part of ideal theory [only briefly alluded to by Rawls] plainly requiring a corresponding third kind of nonideal theory.” 5 This third part of ideal theory will specify a set of ideal (moral) principles to govern individual conduct, and will have its counterpart in nonideal theory that will specify the requirements of individual conduct in nonideal conditions. In each “domain” the nonideal theorist will be confronted both by problems that arise from partial compliance and problems concerning the transition from a less-just to a more-just condition. Some further clarification is warranted with respect to transitional theory in particular. Perhaps most important is Gopal Sreenivasan’s observation that transitional justice, “as it emerges on the second branch of Rawls’ division, means something quite different from what it means in the political science literature burgeoning under the same name” (Sreenivasan (forthcoming)). Basically, issues of “transitional justice” or “transitional theory” in the context of nonideal theory are distinct from discussions of the aftermath of regime change that often go by the same name.6 As I understand it, the main areas of concern within transitional theory are fourfold: (1) costs (2) unfavorable conditions (3) feasibility and (4) path-dependence. I take them up in turn. 2.1 Colin Farrelly rightly observes that in the nonideal world, protecting even the most basic negative rights costs money. This means that trade-offs between these and other primary goods will need to be made. Sreenivasan notes that beyond the costs of merely maintaining the various agencies required to administer services in a just society—such as courts, police, environmental protection, social services, national defense, etc.—there will also be one-time start-up costs associated with making the 2 The grievousness of an injustice is said to be a matter of the extent to which a given institution deviates from perfect justice. It is conceivable that a given reform my make a society more just right now, but will not be consistent with perfect justice-or may even impede its realization. Rawls, TOJ, p. 216. 3 For instance, Sen (2009) criticizes this approach in great detail. Sreenivasan (2007) also suggests an alternative conception of the relationship between ideal and nonideal theory. 4 It is not my intention to present an unorthodox interpretation of Rawls. Instead, I try to work within established interpretations of Rawls’ work as articulated by Simmons (2010) and Moellendorf (1996), among others. Any errors in this regard are purely my own. 5 See Simmons (2010), p. 11, and also Phillips (1985), p. 553. 6 Therefore, questions of retributive and restorative justice that are appropriate to this different notion will not be considered here. Burdened Societies and Transitional Justice 371 theory, then, specifies the end-point or long-term goal to be achieved. The job of nonideal theory is to work toward the ultimate goal of achieving perfect (domestic or international) justice by identifying and proposing solutions to existing injustices, beginning with those that are “most grievous,”—keeping in mind that no single reform should ever prevent us from reaching the end goal.2 This picture has been criticized, but I will not dispute it here.3 Instead, the traditional model will form the background for my discussion. For the sake of argument, I will also assume that a just society is one that approximates Rawls’ conception of justice as fairness.4 Author's personal copy transition from a society without the required institutions to one that has them.7 These are in addition to the personal cost to individuals of bringing their behavior, attitudes and expectations into line with what is required by the new institutions, when they have been socialized under vastly different conditions. Transitional theorists must attempt to assess the costs of various alternative sets of improvements in terms of their efficiency, effectiveness and also in terms of the size and distribution of burdens that they impose, both over time and across various affected groups. 2.2 Since ideal theory assumes reasonably “favorable” or “fortunate” conditions, we should expect that nonideal theory will take into account various types of human misfortune. These misfortunes are the types of occurrence which make it difficult for a given society to achieve justice. Unfavorable conditions can be historical, economic, or social, and we can understand them as largely “inevitable” and “unfortunate” rather than as coming about as a result of deliberate or “clearly avoidable” acts or policies (Simmons (2010), p.15.) Examples of unfavorable economic conditions might be extreme poverty (perhaps due to environmental disasters or lack of development), lack of natural resources, lack of technology or an unworkably low number of working-age citizens (perhaps caused by disease). Social conditions that might be considered unfavorable are certain cultural or social attitudes or norms that make more just conditions undesirable to much of the population (for instance, racism, sexism, ethnic tensions or prejudices, adaptive preferences, a culture of corruption and bribery, or lack of political will). Examples of unfavorable historical conditions might be: deep social or political divides that make cooperative and coordinated reforms very unlikely, or the negative after-effects of colonialism or war. While the precise combination of difficulties will be different for each society, and so no “one-size-fits-all” theoretical solution is possible, there is nevertheless a role for the nonideal theorist to play in developing principles by which we might better understand the most pervasive of these problems, and evaluate proposals for overcoming them. 2.3 When we theorize about the political feasibility of particular reforms we are essentially concerned with the obstacles that stand in the way of realizing a given ideal of justice. While non-compliance and unfavorable conditions are clearly related to feasibility, the focus here is on certain kinds of obstacles. Pablo Gilabert describes these obstacles as depending “not only on general facts about human psychology and social organization, but also on the specific ways these operate in different cultural and institutional settings” (Gilabert (2008), pp. 415). So, concerns about feasibility are, in large part, concerns about those obstacles to realizing justice that arise from human nature generally, as well as specific social contexts. Gilabert notes that arguments about feasibility are highly uncertain and imprecise. He also observes that what is feasible in a given society is “a moving target” since [t]here are moments in which political agents (including, in particular, inspired leaders) reshape and correct perceptions of what is politically possible by pursuing ambitious projects which turn out to be realizable despite initial general dismissal (Gilabert (2008), pp. 416–417). Some reforms may be infeasible due to the kinds of unfavorable historical or social conditions mentioned earlier, or they may arise from brute facts about human nature, such as the desire for power and wealth, or instances of irrationality. Worries about feasibility—when they are plausible—function as reasons why a given society may 7 See Farrelly (2007), p. 850, and also Sreenivasan (forthcoming). 372 L.L. Fuller Author's personal copy not be required to pursue a given course of reform toward a more just society. They act as a kind of excusing condition vis-à-vis certain desirable reforms. However, a plausible argument that a certain reform is infeasible must walk a difficult line, since treating too many elements of the status quo as fixed results in what Gilabert calls “conservative narrowness” while taking too few elements to be fixed results in recommendations that are mere fantasies. 2.4 The term “path dependence” is sometimes used in reference to problems associated with “how to get there from here”, that is, the route a society should take from where it is now to a situation where it approximates the relevant ideal of justice. Simmons notes that if we understand nonideal theory as fundamentally oriented toward achieving a particular end-point, we can see that the best path might in fact lead us to endorse a set of policies or actions that are less just than the status quo, in order to better facilitate arriving at the correct end-point. His basic argument is that we may need “to take one step back in order to take two steps forward,” and that this would be in line with Rawls’ understanding of the role of nonideal theory (Simmons (2010), p. 23). Upon reflection, we can see that not only is Simmons correct that the route to a perfectly just society is not necessarily linear; it is also likely that there are multiple routes that could be taken to the same end-point. Different routes will vary according to their costs, their general moral permissibility, the length of time they will take to implement, and the likelihood of their being realized (rather than thwarted mid-way). I take it to be a central task of nonideal theory to try to imagine and evaluate these routes. Such an evaluation should take account not merely of the efficiency and certainty of a given set of policies in arriving at the end-point, but also the processes that would be utilized to arrive there. As Ingrid Robeyns points out, not all processes are created equal. We might prefer processes that “are respectful and democratic” for instance, over those that are not (Robeyns (2008) p. 350). 3 Burdened Societies Having outlined the key issues facing transitional theory more generally, I’ll now briefly outline Rawls’ concept of a burdened society. Rawls’ general objective in Law of Peoples is to specify an ideal conception of international justice, that is, rules that specify the proper conduct of domestically just states with respect to one another. He generates these rules through a version of the “original position” in which representatives of domestically just peoples come together to deliberate about fair and reasonable rules to regulate their interactions behind a “veil of ignorance.”8 The result of these deliberations, he claims, would yield eight principles of international justice—the details of which need not detain us here—except to note that the sixth and eighth principles require that “Peoples are to honor human rights,” and already well-ordered peoples “have a duty to assist other peoples living under unfavorable conditions that prevent their having a just and decent political and social regime” (Rawls LP, p. 37). Rawls also emphasizes that the “aim of the Law of Peoples will be achieved when all societies have been able to establish either a liberal or a decent regime, however unlikely 8 In this version of the original position, “rational representatives” of peoples are “guided by appropriate reasons,” “situated symmetrically,” and do not know “the size of the territory, or the population, or the relative strength of the people … who they represent… the extent of their natural resources, or the level of their economic development.” Rawls, LP, pp. 32–33. Burdened Societies and Transitional Justice 373 Author's personal copy that may be” (Rawls LP, p. 5). As noted above, for the purposes of this paper, I take liberal societies to be those which approximate Rawls’ model of justice as fairness. By contrast, “decent peoples” are considered well-ordered even though they depart from the ideal model of a liberal society. Decent societies are organized around a particular (religious or secular) conception of the good, and place “duties and obligations on [their] members on the basis of this conception” (Moellendorf (1996) p. 144). John Tasioulas nicely characterizes their additional characteristics as follows: A decent society “has no aggressive aims in foreign policy and respects the political independence of other societies,” “it has a ‘common good idea of justice’ that secures the human rights of all its members, though not necessarily as extensively or as equally as they would be in a liberal society; its legal system imposes bona fide moral duties, beyond those arising from human rights, on all persons within its territory,” and “it affords its members a level of political participation that, although not democratic, suffices to underwrite meaningful collective political self-determination” (Tasioulas (2005), Note 6, p. 15). For simplicity I will assume that decent societies roughly resemble the example Rawls discusses, that is, I will assume that they are “decent consultation hierarchies.”9 Importantly, a decent society is only required to fulfill a minimal schedule of human rights, which includes an entitlement to the basic means of subsistence and physical security, a right to personal property, a right to “sufficient liberty of conscience to ensure freedom of religion and thought” and a right to formal equality understood as the requirement that like cases be treated alike (Rawls LP, p. 65). This minimal schedule does not include fully equal freedom of religion, freedom of speech, or the right to democratic participation. Burdened societies must take steps towards becoming (at least) decent societies, where this is possible. However, they are not required to proceed unaided. In the final section of Law of Peoples, Rawls explains that well-ordered societies have a duty to assist burdened societies so that they may become either liberal or decent. This duty is not an open-ended or ongoing duty of distributive justice. It is merely a duty to assist burdened societies up to the point where they become well-ordered. Thus, the duty has a “cut-off point” after which assistance may be discontinued. Rawls gives some general guidelines that should inform the way the duty of assistance is carried out. First he notes that, The levels of wealth and welfare among societies may vary, and presumably do so; but adjusting those levels is not the object of the duty of assistance. Only burdened societies need help. Furthermore, not all such societies are poor, any more than all well-ordered societies are wealthy. A society with few natural resources and little wealth can be well-ordered if its political traditions, law, property and class structure with their underlying religious and moral beliefs and culture are such as to sustain a liberal or decent society (Rawls LP, p. 106). Next he notes that when carrying out the duty of assistance, well-ordered societies should realize that burdened societies really need help changing their “political and social cultures” rather than simply help amassing more funds (Rawls, LP, p. 108). He cites Amartya Sen’s work on famines as evidence that lack of access to the means subsistence usually results from a failure of political and social institutions rather than mere lack of food or funds. While Rawls asserts that “money is often essential” he also maintains that merely 9 Technically not all liberal societies must endorse justice as fairness, and not all decent peoples will necessarily be decent consultation hierarchies. On Rawls’ account, these are each merely one of the possibilities within each category. (I thank Jon Mandle for bringing this point to my attention). 374 L.L. Fuller Author's personal copy “throwing funds” at the problem is “usually undesirable”, and that “there is no society anywhere in the world—except marginal cases—with resources so scarce that it could not, were it reasonably and rationally organized and governed, become well-ordered (Rawls, LP, pp. 108–109, 110, 108). Finally, well-ordered societies must not act paternalistically in carrying out their duty of assistance, since the goal is that burdened societies will become equals with other well-ordered societies and be able to freely manage their own affairs.10 Rawls locates his discussion of burdened societies within nonideal theory. However, it has been observed by Laura Valentini that Rawls only partially “enters” the nonideal world here. He gives up the assumption of favorable conditions but retains the assumption that there are some reasonably well-ordered societies in existence and that they will (at least sometimes) comply with their duties of assistance. He also seems to overlook the fact that the societies meant to be providing assistance might be implicated in worsening the condition of burdened societies in various ways, such as trading under an unjust international scheme of rules (Valentini (2009), p. 348). I agree with Valentini that failing to bring in these types of real-world considerations “distorts the reality of contemporary international relations,” (Valentini (2009), p. 348). Therefore, I will now attempt to describe the situation of burdened societies in a manner that reflects, at least to some extent, their characteristics and political position in the context of current international relations. It is my view that we will likely make more progress identifying satisfactory transitional principles if we at least try to describe burdened societies in a way that takes account of the kinds of injustices that commonly occur both within and between societies. Basically, in order to develop an account of transitional justice, we need to have some sense of what burdened societies look like in real life. Accordingly, for my purposes here burdened societies are to be understood as having (at least some of) the following sorts of difficulties and characteristics: & They are not aggressive toward other societies, and their governments do not deliberately violate or disregard the human rights of their people. Nevertheless, they do not presently have the ability to fulfill the human rights specified as necessary for becoming even a decent society. & Their economy, for various reasons having to do with technological expertise, lack of education, unfair international rules or agreements, etc., is not as strong as it could be. That is, they make some money but not enough to simply create government entitlements to fulfill the human rights that remain unfulfilled. & A good number of their citizens are very poor-they live at or below the $2-a-day international poverty line.11 Members of the same group are often illiterate and have little formal education. & The society is highly stratified, since there are also very wealthy, educated and powerful individuals within it. (I take this to be true of almost all societies). & Some (but not all) broadly liberal societies provide burdened societies with either bilateral, multilateral or NGO aid, which takes various forms: technical expertise on finance, governance and other policy issues, food, medical and educational programs, etc. However, these programs are only weakly regulated, and the terms are largely 10 Rawls, LP, p. 111. Also note that the use of force as part of an effort to assist burdened societies is ruled out since the societies providing aid are well-ordered and so do not act aggressively towards other societies. 11 The World Bank estimates that 2,561.5 million people lived below the $2 a day poverty line in 2005; As such, it is not an unreasonable assumption that most burdened societies would have a substantial percentage of people living at or below this line. See World Bank, “Prospects for the Global Economy” (2009) at http:// siteresources.worldbank.org/INTGEP2009/Resources/10363_WebPDF-01Chapter1-w47.pdf . Burdened Societies and Transitional Justice 375 Author's personal copy http://siteresources.worldbank.org/INTGEP2009/Resources/10363_WebPDF-01Chapter1-w47.pdf http://siteresources.worldbank.org/INTGEP2009/Resources/10363_WebPDF-01Chapter1-w47.pdf dictated by the donors. Here we are assuming that only some percentage of well-ordered societies will comply with the duty to assist burdened societies. This is one of the unfavorable conditions in which they find themselves. & Their society has its share of historically disadvantaged groups and so will have to contend with some (if not all of) sexism, racism, homophobia and discrimination against certain ethnicities or members of certain religions. & They may also have to contend with their members’ adaptive preferences, and/or corruption among civil servants, police officers and other people in a position to wield power over others. & They may have weak bargaining power in the international arena. & As in Rawls, they may not already have in place a legal structure guaranteeing the full and equal civil and political liberties that are in place in most liberal democracies. They may be proto-democracies (that is, they officially have the form of democratic government but their elections and other practices are not up to par). Alternatively, they could be proto-decent-consultation-hierarchies (in which they have a political system based on a particular conception of the good but that is also somewhat tainted by considerations of personal interest, say, among elites and the military). Here then, is a significantly more detailed picture of burdened societies than the one given by Rawls. What we now want to know is how such a society should approach the task of making itself more just. We shall suppose for the sake of argument that a particular society accepts that it must take steps toward becoming either liberal or decent (as set out by ideal theory). What should this society—including its government—do now? Is there anything general we can say about the way it ought to proceed? It is to these questions that I now turn.12 4 What Would Rawls(ians) Say? Rawls himself says relatively little on the subject of how a society should handle the transition from a less-just to a more-just condition. Much of what he does say appears in Theory of Justice, and so presupposes that the ideal to be reached is a liberal democratic society rather than merely a decent society. As we have seen, however, some burdened societies may only aim to become decent given their particular comprehensive doctrines. These considerations lead me to divide this section into two distinct parts. First, I will do my best to give a broadly Rawlsian account of transitional justice where the goal is to become a perfectly just liberal democratic society. Next, I attempt the same task where the goal is to become a decent society. In both cases I assume that the society begins as a burdened society, and so it has, roughly, the characteristics and difficulties described in the previous section.13 12 I do not mean to suggest that these questions are ones Rawls either did, or should have, addressed. They are not his questions, since he was mainly concerned with outlining a duty of assistance on the part of well- ordered societies. However, note that the answers to these questions must be part of a complete transitional theory, especially given that the duty of assistance is meant to be non-paternalistic and so its content must be in large part concretely determined by burdened societies themselves. (Many thanks to Steve Vanderheiden for this last observation). 13 Of course, transitions from a less-just to a more-just condition will be necessary for societies that are not “burdened” but are still unjust. Whether a society is burdened or not depends on the extent of the unfavorable circumstances in which it finds itself, particularly economically. Societies that are not burdened, but still have some injustices to correct, should be understood to be unjust societies in favorable conditions. 376 L.L. Fuller Author's personal copy 4.1 Transitioning to a Liberal Democratic Society The Rawlsian model of justice as fairness specifies that a perfectly just liberal democratic society is one where the basic structure is organized in conformity with the following two principles: 1. Each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive total system of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar system for all [the Liberty Principle]. 2. Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are both: (a) to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged … [the Difference Principle] and (b) attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity.14 The first principle is lexically prior to the second, and fair equality of opportunity is lexically prior to the difference principle. Further, for Rawls the “ranking of the principles of justice in ideal theory reflects back and guides the application of these principles to nonideal situations. It identifies which restrictions need to be dealt with first” (Rawls TOJ, p. 267). Clearly he thinks that guaranteeing the basic liberties should be the first priority of unjust societies. Reforms that restrict basic liberties are permissible, but only for the sake of liberty, which, on Simmons view, means that “restrictions on liberty are acceptable only if they are part of a process aimed at achieving the fullest possible societal justice” (Simmons (2010), p. 15). For instance, liberties such as free speech or association can be limited or made unequal if this is needed for the general order of society and the security of citizens, provided that these are temporary measures, and are aimed at the end of perfect justice. On Simmons’ interpretation, such temporary measures “do not really count as injustices” so long as they are “motivated by and directed toward” the correct end (Simmons (2010), p. 16). Thus, the priority of liberty is the main principle of transitional justice that Rawls spells out in Theory of Justice. However, Rawls also notes that “in the more extreme and tangled instances of nonideal theory… [the] priority of rules will no doubt fail; and indeed, we may be able to find no satisfactory answer at all” (Rawls TOJ, p. 267). Simmons comments that for those unlucky societies where social conditions are such that the basic liberties cannot be established, Rawls favors a more piecemeal or “relaxed” approach to transitional issues. Simmons observes, In this kind of case—Rawls appears to be thinking, primarily at least, of cases involving severe societal poverty—“one can concede their [i.e. rights] limitations,” but only where this limitation is “necessary to prepare the way for a free society by “raising the level of civilization” … In this case, Rawls suggests, society should be governed primarily by the general conception of justice, which lacks the lexically ordered principles of ideal theory, until it becomes reasonable, as a result of “improvement in economic well-being” to be guided by the two separate principles of ideal theory in their serial order. The general conception dictates that over the long run lesser liberties for all must benefit all, while unequal liberties must benefit those with lesser liberties (Simmons (2010) pp. 13–14). Rawls also allows that in such dire conditions, policies which violate fair equality of opportunity or depart from a system of equal basic liberties, “have the right form when they 14 Rawls, TOJ, p. 266. The basic liberties Rawls lists as “important” are the right to vote and hold office, freedom of speech and assembly, the right to bodily integrity and freedom from psychological oppression, freedom from arbitrary arrest and seizure, freedom of conscience and thought, and the right to hold personal property. Rawls, TOJ, p. 53. Burdened Societies and Transitional Justice 377 Author's personal copy claim … that the opportunities of the least favored sectors of the community would be still more limited if these inequalities were removed” (Rawls TOJ, p. 265). Some inequalities can be tolerated in very unfavorable conditions, provided that it makes sense to leave them in place from the perspective of the worst-off. Now, we might well think that on Rawls’ account burdened societies are extreme cases in which the priority of the liberty principle does not apply, and/or societies in which the basic liberties are not realizable. The problem with conceiving of burdened societies on this more “relaxed” model is that, as we have seen, Rawls thinks that virtually all existing societies have enough resources such that they can become well-ordered, and so must realize the most central liberties first where this is feasible (Rawls TOJ, pp. 217–218). Basically, while in Theory of Justice he admits the conceptual possibility of a society that could not effectively establish basic rights, in Law of Peoples he seems to suggest that there is no real society that is in so dire a condition. Of course, whether or not any society is sufficiently impoverished that it cannot effectively establish the basic rights is an empirical question. From a theoretical perspective then, the more “relaxed” approach remains an option for societies in this predicament. So it looks like burdened societies still must assign lexical priority to the basic liberties, at least when this is not completely infeasible. Presumably, where this is completely infeasible in a given set of circumstances, all possible “lateral moves” should be pursued that would put a burdened society in a position to apply the priority-of-liberty rule. This would mean that where a society can move from one unjust condition to another that is equally unjust but that opens up feasible reforms that would bring them closer to realizing the basic liberties, then they should do so. This is because the priority-of-liberty rule effectively establishes the “grievousness” of any particular injustice, and so the urgency with which a society should respond.15 Beyond what can be extrapolated from Rawls emphasis on the priority of the basic liberties, we are left with his three further requirements: that transitional policies and courses of action must be (i) morally permissible, (ii) politically possible, and (iii) effective. We are unfortunately left wondering both how we are to interpret each requirement, and how we are to weigh them against one another, since Rawls does not tell us. Of the three requirements, moral permissibility seems the most problematic to interpret. Simmons provides three plausible understandings: a. Policies are morally permissible when they do not require or condone clearly immoral acts by public officials in order to be instituted. b. Policies are permissible when they do not require a more grievous injustice to be instituted in order to remedy a less grievous one. c. Policies are permissible when they do not impose excessive costs or burdens on individual citizens in order to be instituted, as in the case where people suffer substantial losses because they have organized their affairs around the previous (less just) set of institutions and expectations (Simmons (2010), p. 21). It seems to me that a broadly Rawlsian account might endorse any and perhaps all of these understandings depending on the circumstances, and I will adopt these requirements as part of my own approach. It also seems that if we combine Rawls’ emphasis on the priority of liberty with the guidelines for assistance to burdened societies, we can infer that 15 By lexically ordering the principles, Rawls establishes that violations of the first principle are more grievous than violations of fair equality of opportunity or the difference principle, since the priority is based on the importance of liberties to deliberators in the original position. 378 L.L. Fuller Author's personal copy burdened societies will accept aid that will help them guarantee basic liberties, except when the assistance is paternalistic in nature, since this can undermine the point of the assistance. The difficulty here is that in a genuinely nonideal world, much assistance is likely to be paternalistic in nature, or at least have some paternalistic conditions attached to it. Thus, it looks like there is a tension between the requirement that a burdened society work to become more just domestically and the requirements of international justice. Farrelly argues that there are deep difficulties with a model that assigns lexical priority to the liberty principle, and I tend to agree with him. His main argument is that Rawls fails to take the fact of scarcity seriously. He notes that even in a reasonably well-off society, guaranteeing basic liberties could turn out to be “a never-ending aim” since it is possible for a society to allocate all their wealth to making streets and borders secure, ensuring food and drugs are safe, protecting citizens from police brutality, etc. (Farrelly (2007), p. 852ff). In essence, Farrelly observes that trade-offs will be necessary in every society, and so the lexical priority of basic liberties over opportunities and other social and economic entitlements is unhelpful. He also questions Rawls’ contention that trade-offs between liberties and social and economic advantages are impermissible even when the advantages go to the same individuals whose liberties are restricted. It certainly seems plausible that citizens in burdened societies might sometimes choose to have fewer civil liberties in return for more economic advantages, if trade-offs must be made. And there is no distributive difficulty here when it is the same individuals who bear the burdens and obtain the benefits. The problem here is that people may prefer to guarantee fewer liberties, or leave them less secure, in order to allocate funds to other areas, even when total funds are sufficient to guarantee all the basic liberties but not much else in addition. For many burdened societies, scarcity is likely to be a much larger concern than for societies in more favorable conditions. This means that it is more likely that there will be situations in which guaranteeing civil liberties leaves very few resources left over to institute the difference principle and fair equality of opportunity. As such, opting for the lexical priority of the liberty principle seems to unfairly disadvantage those people most likely to desire trade-offs in favor of more economic advantages, namely, the very poorest in society.16 A more flexible approach to both the kind of protections and benefits that will be prioritized as well as who will receive them seems desirable, given that there is no choice but to make difficult trade-offs. As such, assigning lexical priority to basic liberties does not seem like a viable overall strategy for burdened societies—given their unfavorable conditions—even if the society in question did aspire to become a liberal democracy. 4.2 Transitioning to a Decent Society As we have seen, some societies may not aspire to become liberal, but instead may merely aim to become decent, such that they may be admitted into the Society of Peoples. Since those in a decent society do not embrace a liberal conception of justice, but instead organize their society on the basis of a particular comprehensive doctrine and a “common good idea of justice,” they are not required to institute the full range of basic liberties. Hence, they also are not required to proceed towards their goal by prioritizing these liberties. Instead, they 16 To be fair, Rawls allows that “the first principle covering the equal basic rights and liberties may easily be preceded by a lexically prior principle requiring that citizens’ basic needs be met, at least insofar as their being met is necessary for citizens to understand and to be able to fruitfully exercise those rights” (Rawls (1996), p. 7). Rawls is not here recommending that people prioritize the protection of civil liberties over their very survival. Burdened Societies and Transitional Justice 379 Author's personal copy must work towards a situation in which they can guarantee the fulfillment of a minimal list of human rights (rights to subsistence and security, freedom from slavery, serfdom and forced occupation, freedom of worship, formal legal equality and the right to personal property), and are subject to the three requirements of moral permissibility, political possibility, and effectiveness (Rawls LP, p. 65). They must accept assistance in this effort, (when this assistance is not paternalistic), especially in changing their political and social culture, since Rawls claims that “the causes of the wealth of a people and the forms it takes lie in their political culture and the religious, philosophical and moral traditions that support the basic structure of their political and social institutions, as well as the industriousness and cooperative talents of its members” (Rawls LP, p. 108). The specific elements of the political and social culture he describes as crucial to a society’s ability to become both wealthier and more decent are as follows: the political culture and civic society of the country, it members’ probity and industriousness, their talent for cooperation, their capacity for innovation, and their population policy. Rawls admits that there is “no easy recipe” for providing assistance that will help a burdened society make the required changes, and so perhaps this is why he does not attempt to prescribe which human rights should rank highest in terms of priority. He also does not indicate how burdened societies should go about realizing their aims, although he observes approvingly that educating women has been shown to be a good, non-coercive way to institute population control (Rawls LP, p. 110). Rawls also agrees with Henry Shue that subsistence rights are basic, in the sense that the “sensible and rational exercise of all liberties … as well as the intelligent use of property, always implies having general all-purpose economic means” (Rawls LP, Note 1, p. 65). We might infer from this that guaranteeing subsistence rights should be the top priority for societies aspiring to become decent, which seems like a reasonable recommendation for burdened societies. This general approach to becoming a decent society can be summed up as follows: Starting with subsistence rights, a burdened society should implement effective policies in morally permissible ways that are ultimately aimed at fulfilling a minimal schedule of human rights for its people. It also should accept non-paternalistic assistance in this effort from well-ordered societies. This approach looks more promising for burdened societies than the former one. However, it may be Rawls’ position that beyond this point we simply have to employ our intuitions and arguments in reference to the concrete situation of each real society; Perhaps he would assert that there is nothing more that we can say, in general, about how burdened societies should make the transition to decent or liberal societies. I disagree. In the next section, I attempt to modify and flesh out this second approach in more detail. My hope is that this modified approach will provide resources for both prescribing and evaluating the transitional efforts of actual societies approximating the condition of burdened societies. A central advantage of the approach is that it will be able to provide some direction to the well-ordered societies carrying out their duties of assistance with regard to which societies they ought to support. Where not all burdened societies can be assisted (or at least not to the same degree), my account provides a guideline for identifying those societies that are not only moving in the right direction, but also doing so in the right way, and so are most worthy of outside assistance. 5 Transitional Justice for Burdened Societies: A Proposal The approach I sketch out here is arguably Rawlsian “in spirit” since Rawls’ notion of the “worst-off representative person” is key to the structure of the model. Before I can describe 380 L.L. Fuller Author's personal copy my approach in detail however, I need to explain how I think this notion should be understood in a nonideal context, and why. A difficulty for both accounts of transitional justice discussed above and also for many accounts of human rights is that they are too neat. No doubt for conceptual and explanatory purposes, they treat rights as distinct entities and assess injustice on the basis of the extent to which a society fails to fulfill each particular one. Even when it is recognized that guaranteeing a right entails both “negative” and “positive” duties (such as setting up social institutions) this kind of approach leads us to think of rights as separate from one another in an artificial and misleading way. 17 This merely conceptual separation, in turn, causes us to think in terms of fulfilling human rights by first completely fulfilling the most morally important right (or set of rights), and then the next most important, and then the next, and so on. The problem with this is that injustice is not typically experienced and embodied as a set of distinct rights violations or lack of rights fulfillment, each one having little influence on the others. Instead, a victim of injustice is usually subject to a confluence of factors that produce a very particular condition of vulnerability. It is often observed that when human rights are fulfilled they are mutually reinforcing, and so it stands to reason that injustices are too. It is also not news that the way a black woman experiences poverty in a racist and sexist society is not the same as the way a white man experiences it. Nevertheless, I think the significance of these observations for a theory of transitional justice has not been properly appreciated. Paul Farmer suggests that insofar as we are concerned with alleviating injustice, we need to “identify the forces conspiring to promote suffering, with the understanding that these are differentially weighted in different settings” (Farmer (2010), p. 344). He furthers asserts that if we can identify these forces, then “we stand a chance at discerning … the forces that put some at risk for human rights abuses, while others are shielded from risk” ” (Farmer (2010), p. 344). The notion of multiple, intersecting “vectors” of injustice is illuminating. The forces, or vectors that he specifically mentions are: race or ethnicity, gender, poverty, immigration status (such as refugees, illegal aliens or stateless people), and sexual orientation.18 He notes that being subject to more than one such vector increases a person’s overall vulnerability, and those people who are not subject to them have certain characteristics that serve a protective function. For instance, being white can protect a young male from being regularly stopped and searched (for largely opaque or spurious reasons) by the police in most US cities. Even if a white man is identically placed with respect to other characteristics (such as income level) his whiteness serves to protect him from this particular sort of injustice. Farmer argues that no single factor can fully capture the level of vulnerability of a particular person. Poverty, for instance, might cancel out many of the protective effects of characteristics such as being of the dominant race, religion or sexual orientation in your society, but these factors are still relevant to where you are located within the social hierarchy. So how are these vectors of injustice relevant to issues of transitional justice? This understanding of how injustice manifests itself suggests that we need to alter the way we think about the worst-off person in a burdened society. What we need is a nonideal account of the “worst-off representative person.” First, we should recall that the society in question 17 In his classic book Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence and US Foreign Policy (1980) Henry Shue argues persuasively that the distinction between negative and positive rights is neither sharp nor significant. 18 Clearly there are vectors other than these. Also, “vector” is my terminology. Farmer prefers the term “axis”. He also cites some material from liberation theology in this connection, but it should be understood that I am not invoking that tradition here. See Farmer (2010), pp. 337–341. Burdened Societies and Transitional Justice 381 Author's personal copy is already highly stratified, and so there are people highly placed in the social hierarchy whose human rights are already fulfilled due to the protective characteristics they possess, such as great wealth, political influence, a good education, etc. Next, rather than understanding the worst-off representative person—as Rawls does in Theory of Justice— as someone whose basic rights are, in large part, already guaranteed but who must authorize any departures from equality in the social and economic realms, instead we should understand the worst-off person as the person who is living at the intersection of the most numerous/weightiest vectors of injustice in her society. This is the person (or group of people) whose unfulfilled rights should structure efforts to make the society more just. By identifying this representative person, we identify the problems that should be prioritized, since these people are suffering the most from injustice. And in a society where trade-offs must be made, policies should be organized with a view to eliminating the difficulties that typically threaten the lives and livelihoods of the worst-off people. In particular, policies should be organized such that the common threats and difficulties that distinguish them from the next-worst-off group should be the first problems that are tackled in the context of very limited resources. My suggestion here is that transitional justice requires burdened societies to prioritize a group of people and their urgent, concrete vulnerabilities, rather than their “rights” in some abstract and comprehensive sense. Clearly, much social scientific work will be needed in order for the relevant vectors in any particular society to be correctly identified and weighted. But once we see that groups of people within each burdened society can be ranked from the worst-off to the best-off on the basis of how they fare with respect to the vectors, then we can see whose lives are the most marred by adverse events that occur due to the mutually- reinforcing multiple injustices that they suffer. And we can propose solutions to their problems that take account of the fact that multiple rights violations are experienced by people as a single condition—a condition in which they are exposed to various harms and setbacks for a host of related reasons. Consider the following example: “B” grows up in a rural area, where most people engage in subsistence farming for a living, but the yields are not adequate to support everyone in his family. Once he is a teenager he moves to the city to find work and to relieve his family of the burden of providing for him. However, since he belongs to a minority group that is not universally accepted by employers of a different ethnicity, and because has no formal education, he is only able to secure a very low-paying job. This means he must live in a shantytown or slum outside the city center, where he does not have to pay rent. But since he is, legally-speaking, a squatter on the land where he lives, he is subject to repeated harassment and abuse by the police.19 This, in turn, causes him to miss work sometimes and to be unwell. He is then not always able to make enough money to purchase food that can provide adequate nutrition, which makes him worse-off still… Assume for the sake of argument that B is part of the worst-off group in his society. We can see that there are many ways in which his life can be made more secure from physical abuse and injury, and his ability to provide for his own subsistence can also be improved (by for example, making his living arrangements legal). We can also see that solutions to those problems that are specific to people in the worst-off group are not going to require that the society institute a comprehensive system of protections against assault, hunger, sickness etc., since many people in his society are already protected from these threats anyhow. Solutions to B’s specific set of vulnerabilities should be tailored to the risks that 19 Many of the global poor rank ending police brutality and harassment very highly on a list of improvements they would like to see in their lives. See Narayan et al. (2000), pp. 35–36 and 27. 382 L.L. Fuller Author's personal copy those in his group actually face. This means that these solutions will not necessarily require fully guaranteed rights in the sense set out by Shue, in which a right is only guaranteed when the relevant agents have fulfill the following three kinds of corresponding duties: (1) the duties to avoid depriving someone of their right, (2) duties to protect from deprivation, and (3) duties to aid those who have been deprived of the exercise or object of their right (Shue (1980), p. 52). Instead, sometimes a given source of vulnerability can be most effectively, and/or most feasibly be eliminated or substantially diminished by instituting a policy that does only one (or two) of the three. This is the correct strategy in terms of effectiveness because the way to genuinely improve the circumstances of the worst-off representative person is by taking a holistic approach, that is, by instituting policies that are aimed at the set of factors which make him worse-off than the next-worse-off representative person. Simply securing one right in full leaves this person open to it being sabotaged by the difficulties and adverse events correlated with other rights violations. For example, say a society-wide policy of improved policing and other measures are put in place to guarantee everyone’s security of the person, or freedom from physical assault. If someone cannot find work and must resort to illegal activities (prostitution, selling drugs, trafficking in stolen goods) in order to survive, then that person’s vulnerability to physical assault (from pimps, rivals, etc.) is simply “driven underground” rather than eliminated. This demonstrates why policy-makers should take a coordinated approach to making the worst-off group better off, which means doing what is necessary to bring the worst-off people up to the level of the next worst-off group. Of course, once this has been accomplished, it will be necessary to begin addressing the problems of that group, since its members are now the worst-off (and so on up through the social hierarchy). I should emphasize at this point that when I suggest that policies should address the common threats and difficulties experienced by the worst-off group of people, I do not mean that they should somehow be protected from all possible threats and vulnerabilities. Instead, I have in mind a notion similar to Shue’s notion of “standard threats,” which he defines as “ordinary and serious but remediable” (Shue (1980, p. 32). Protecting someone from “standard threats” according to Shue, is a matter of providing social guarantees (in the form of policies, legislation and social programs) that vastly reduces or eliminates their vulnerability to predictable difficulties that are susceptible to determinate (and not unreasonably costly) solutions. He rightly observes that no one is entitled to protection from “every conceivable threat,” or “ineradicable threats” such as untreatable serious illnesses, accidents, or death, since this would be impossible.20 What count as standard threats for any particular group will be determined by social scientific study, but these threats will no doubt show up in answer to questions such as: “What are the common causes of death in this group?” and “How do members of this group typically become deprived of the means of subsistence?” Having set out the basic framework, I can now comment on its justification. If we consider Rawls’ requirement that transitional reforms be morally permissible, we can see that prioritarian arguments give this approach a solid moral grounding. Dennis McKerlie characterizes prioritarianism as follows: [Prioritarianism] holds that, at least in general, badly off people have stronger claims than better off people. … It does not claim that as a general rule we can give the 20 Shue also notes that the “mixture of the analytic and the empirical in an element like standard threats is obviously difficult to characterize with any precision. …But which threats are pervasive, which are serious, and which can feasibly be resisted must be discovered from particular situations,” (Shue 1980 Note 22, p. 184). Burdened Societies and Transitional Justice 383 Author's personal copy 384 L.L. Fuller badly off larger benefits, it claims that benefits for them are morally more important than benefits for better off people. So this view can say that it is more important to give a smaller benefit to someone badly off than a larger benefit to someone better off (McKerlie (1994), pp. 25–26). Not only is it morally permissible on this view to help the worst-off, it is morally more important to do so. Provided that the reforms do not call for the unjustified use of coercive force for their implementation, it is plausible to think that addressing direct harms to the worst-off that result from injustice is a morally sound method by which to tackle injustice generally, since inevitably some criterion must be used to prioritize reforms. For those not persuaded by a prioritarian view, there is an alternative justification to consider. We can imagine a kind of nonideal “original position” in which all the facts about a real burdened society are known to the deliberators, but they remain ignorant of the characteristics they will have once they join the society. If asked—before being transformed into the selves they will be in society—which injustices they would choose to remedy if they could not remedy them all, a maximin strategy would suggest that they would choose the injustices that affect the worst-off people, since they could turn out to be those people. Even if the improved condition of those people is still not very good, they will probably prefer to minimize risk, since the risks to the worst-off people in a burdened society are very great, and they include many risks to survival itself. Finally, this model conforms to the requirements of moral permissibility introduced earlier, since it starts with the most grievous injustices—understood as the condition of injustice the worst-off experience as a result of the intersecting vectors to which they are subject. In addition, the holistic nature of the approach allows for the worst-off to be “lifted up” to the level of the next-worst-off and so there is no danger of one group being subject to a more grievous injustice in order to rectify another group’s unjust condition. Further, in this model the best-off members of society bear the greatest burden, in the sense that they will benefit the least from reforms and will wait the longest for reforms that benefit them to be instituted. This is as it should be, since members who are located near the bottom of the social hierarchy already bear the heavy burden of diminished welfare and liberty, relative to those at the top. By contrast, one might imagine a transitional process in which a burdened society becomes more just by first guaranteeing the rights it is easiest to guarantee, namely those of the middle and upper classes, after which they make slow incremental gains in securing some rights to the bottom economic quartile of society. Such a society, even if it were to ultimately become just or decent by such a process, would not have arrived there in a transitionally just manner, since it placed the burdens of transition on those who were already the most vulnerable. The general justification for my approach is further supported by additional arguments pertaining to feasibility, cost and path dependence. Clearly reforms need to be politically and practically feasible in order for them to be implemented. It wouldn’t make sense to require that a given society implement policies aimed at the difficulties of the worst-off, if these policies were genuinely impossible to implement at particular time. This situation could arise either because the reforms have no popular support or because political disagreement among factions has reached an impasse. However, it seems implausible that all available methods of addressing all the vulnerabilities of the worst-off group will be blocked by these kinds of circumstances. Certainly creativity will be vital for generating political agreement and garnering support for programs from citizens. And in cases where a given Author's personal copy problem cannot be addressed in the short-term, it must be considered an ongoing priority in the long term, and so should be addressed when better circumstances are in place. Moving on to cost issues, the model requires that funds be directed first towards those difficulties that distinguish members of the worst-off group from the next-worst-off. Clearly it makes the most sense to choose those that are also least costly to solve, since this is more efficient, but cheaper coercive measures should not be favored over non-coercive ones purely for this reason. Policies that do not seek to coerce members of the worst-off group are to be strongly preferred because they are already so vulnerable to those who are more powerful that it is unreasonable to subject them to more risk of abuse. In any case, policies that require immoral conduct (such as unjustified coercion) on the part of officials are already ruled out. The question everyone wants answered when discussing the start-up and maintenance costs of transitional policies and programs is “Where will all the money come from, when we are discussing a society that has a substantial group of very poor members?” This question often leads people to suggest that what is needed is a “growth-led” policy, in which growing the economy is made the priority, and transitional policies are put-off until a society is richer overall and so can afford to roll out large, expensive programs. This strategy typically also recommends de-regulating trade, labor standards, and offering other incentives in order to attract foreign investment. While there is some reason to think that it is not necessary to put-off reforms in order to first generate funds, even without resolving this controversy we can say that any foreign aid that a burdened society receives can be used in a manner consistent with the model. This would mean, however, that foreign aid which was offered with conditions that would cause additional difficulties for the worst-off group would have to be rejected or re-negotiated in order to accord with this notion of transitional justice. This is likely to be a “sticking point” for some well-ordered societies since they most likely do not wish simply to aid the burdened society but also to take advantage of the cheap labor or other conditions prevailing there in order to make money themselves. But such exploitative international practices would not help a given society to reach its goal of becoming decent, and so it is not morally permissible to accept such offers. Additional funding for reforms could come from taxation of wealthy members of the society, and from NGOs. This will require burdened societies to monitor NGOs and approve the content of the work they seek to do before they do it. This monitoring will itself be a cost, but it will also allow the government of a given society to serve a coordinating function for NGOs within its borders that is sorely lacking in the aid system overall. This lack of coordination is one reason that NGO aid has not historically been as effective as expected, and so taking a holistic approach to serving the worst-off may also create overall efficiency gains for NGO aid. Finally, a note on path dependence: Even someone well-disposed toward the general account I have put forward might wonder whether the path of reform it recommends will lead burdened societies towards either decency or liberal democracy in the long run. A critic might suggest that while my approach seems justifiable in the short-run, a piecemeal, bottom-up model of this kind is unlikely to result in anything approximating the standard of decency or the model of perfect justice. Instead, it might result in a society getting “stuck” in a second-, or third-, or fourth-best condition with no further routes for improvement. In response to this concern, I will first observe that such claims are highly speculative and imprecise. I have difficulty conceiving of what it would mean for someone to “know for sure” that a given path of reform could never lead to the chosen end-point (whatever it is). It is also difficult to understand how we could know that of the very many routes that could lead to the chosen end-point, that not even one would approximate the model I have Burdened Societies and Transitional Justice 385 Author's personal copy endorsed. But supposing that we could know this, I think my approach might be defended on the grounds that one of the reasons we care about justice is that we care about how well- off people are, and this approach puts the right people first. In addition, it matters very much how close we could come to the desired end-point while at the same time prioritizing the worst-off. If we could come reasonably close, then this might well be better all things considered than achieving perfect justice or decency at the expense of those whose lives are already collapsing under the weight of multiple injustices. 6 Conclusion I have attempted two distinct tasks: (i) to re-construct Rawls’ conception of transitional justice in both Theory of Justice and Law of Peoples, and (ii) to expand and modify the latter conception in order to apply it to burdened societies. I have also introduced the notion of multiple, intersecting “vectors” of injustice in order to generate an account of the worst- off representative person for nonideal theory. While this notion is no doubt relevant to all societies that are not perfectly just, it seems to me it is especially crucial for charting a defensible course towards a more just condition for those societies that must begin this process in unfavorable circumstances, such as extreme scarcity of resources, pervasive corruption, deeply rooted prejudice and discrimination, and severe social inequality. Acknowledgements I am grateful to audiences at both the North American Society for Social Philosophy Conference (July 2010) and the Rocky Mountain Ethics Congress (August 2010) for their excellent feedback. I would also like to thank Steve Vanderheiden, Helga Varden and Jon Mandle for their detailed and insightful comments on earlier drafts of this article. References Farmer P (2010) On suffering and structural violence: social and economic rights in the global era. In: Saussy H (ed) Partner to the poor: a Paul Farmer reader. University of California Press, Berkeley, pp 328–349 Farrelly C (2007) Justice in ideal theory: a refutation. Polit Stud 55:844–864 Gilabert P (2008) Global justice and poverty relief in nonideal circumstances. Soc Theor Pract 34:411–438 McKerlie D (1994) Equality and priority. Utilitas 6:25–42 Moellendorf D (1996) Constructing the law of peoples. Pac Phil Q 77:132–154 Narayan D et al (2000) Voices of the poor: crying out for change. Oxford University Press for The World Bank, New York Phillips M (1985) Reflections on the transition from ideal to non-ideal theory. Noûs 19:551–570 Rawls J (1996) Political liberalism. Columbia University Press, New York Rawls J (1999a) Theory of justice, Revised Edition. Harvard University Press, Cambridge Rawls J (1999b) Law of peoples. Harvard University Press, Cambridge Robeyns I (2008) Ideal theory in theory and practice. Soc Theor Pract 34:341–362 Sen A (2009) The idea of justice. Belknap, Cambridge Shue H (1980) Basic rights: subsistence, affluence and US foreign policy. Princeton University Press, Princeton Simmons AJ (2010) Ideal and nonideal theory. Phil Pub Affairs 38:5–36 Sreenivasan G (2007) Health and justice in our nonideal world. Polit Philos Econ 6:218–236 Sreenivasan G (forthcoming) What is non-ideal theory? In: Williams M, Elster J (eds) Transitional justice. New York University Press, New York. Tasioulas J (2005) Global justice without end? Metaphilosophy 36:3–29 Valentini L (2009) On the apparent paradox of ideal theory. J Polit Philos 17:332–355 386 L.L. Fuller Author's personal copy Burdened Societies and Transitional Justice Abstract Introduction Notes on Non-ideal Theory Burdened Societies What Would Rawls(ians) Say? Transitioning to a Liberal Democratic Society Transitioning to a Decent Society Transitional Justice for Burdened Societies: A Proposal Conclusion References work_6l53i65qvnf47ltk45xn5vrvfa ---- AMS Skip to main content Menu AMS Open Search Close Search Search the site: Main navigation (extended config) Academics+ Program Learning Outcomes Major Minor Current Course Offerings Academic Year Course Offering AMS Program+ Why be an AMS Major? Alumni People+ Faculty Lecturers Emeritus Faculty Staff Student+ Advising Emphasis Plan Senior Capstone Internship Prizes Transfer Students Letters of Recommendation Resources for Students AMS AT 50+ American Studies at UC Davis: Breaking Down Walls for 50 Years CAREN KAPLAN RETIREMENT SYMPOSIUM         Welcome! Founded during the 1968-69 school year, American Studies Department at UC Davis stands apart as the only department of its kind in the University of California system. In its 50 + years on campus it has been dedicated to creating an interdisciplinary space for students to connect their personal curiosities and concerns to broader public issues, histories, and materials.  What is American Studies? When you hear the phrase "American Studies," you might think of classrooms decked out in red, white, and blue; classes that feel just like your 10th grade U.S. history class; and images of Uncle Sam and Captain America. If you walk through our wing on the second floor of Hart Hall, you'll see that's not the case. The American Studies Department at Davis (AMS at UCD) looks at American culture as a compilation of things that can be questioned and analyzed. And it uses many lenses to understand the complicated, messy, and diverse lives people live in both in the United States and in an interconnected world. As an interdisciplinary department, AMS at UCD pulls from several disciplines (history, literature, environmental science, food science, sociology, and more) to explore phenomena in and related to U.S. culture. The faculty study food, prisons, the environment, artificial sweeteners, music, militarized culture, and much more. Each of them asks questions and teaches classes to help all of us make sense of the world we live in. So, in American Studies classes at Davis, you'll find folks asking questions about drones, thinking about the boom of diversity in comics, studying the California rodeo, analyzing the role of gossip in specific communities, wondering what needs to happen to save our planet, how to tie social science justice and academic research, and more.  Why study American Studies at Davis?  AMS at UCD has spent the last 50+ years grappling with questions of American-ness. The department isn't afraid to shy away from the personal and the political. You'll find that many of our faculty study topics that are near and dear to their hearts. AMS at UCD is a place for rigorous study and "making sense" of what's important to you. It's a place to ask big (and sometimes hard and scary) questions to better understand the world. American Studies Association Statement on BLM & Rebellion of 2020 Asian American Studies Association Statement on Atlanta Why be an American Studies Major? Our alumni are now lawyers, teachers, social workers, urban planners, marketing professionals, software engineers, filmmakers, professors, professional writers (and comedians) and non-profit staff and leaders. If this appeals to you, you might fit well in our community. If you have questions or curiosities about the diverse cultures that make up the U.S., AMS at UCD might be for you. If you want individualized attention, a major that lets you explore multiple disciplines, and the chance to study topics that are important to you, take a class with us or reach out to our major advisor and our undergraduate faculty advisor.  Contact Us Visit our advising office at 1203 Hart Hall (First floor). Closed due to COVID-19. Email general inquiries to ams-advising@ucdavis.edu. To contact individual faculty, see faculty listing. Call the American Studies office at 530-752-6429. Social Media Links Main Office 1203 Hart Hall (First floor) University of California, Davis  One Shields Avenue  Davis, CA 95616  Contact Us Visit our advising office at 1203 Hart Hall (First floor).  Email general inquiries to ams-advising@ucdavis.edu. To contact individual faculty, see faculty listing. Call the American Studies office at 530-752-6429. Join our Facebook group for news and announcements. Admin Links Login Webmaster UC Davis College of Letters and Science | Social Sciences and Humanities Building | 530-752-0394 University of California, Davis, One Shields Avenue, Davis, CA 95616 | 530-752-1011 Questions or comments? Privacy & Accessibility Principles of Community University of California Sitemap Last update: March 22, 2021 Copyright © The Regents of the University of California, Davis campus. All rights reserved. This site is officially grown in SiteFarm. work_6l74bfvwkbg3llgqdjpfjcthdu ---- CULTURE AND SOCIETY After Madoff: Waiting for Justice Lionel S. Lewis Published online: 27 January 2011 # Springer Science+Business Media, LLC 2011 This essay examines how Madoff’s victims adapted to their suddenly diminished financial security, status, and self image after learning that they had been swindled. The primary foci are: (1) What they were thinking and feeling about their changed circumstances and (2) How they were coping with them. To best answer these and other questions, during the summer of 2010—approximately a year after Madoff was incarcerated—letters and e-mails were sent to all but seven of the initial list of 167 victims asking for up-to-date descriptions of family, financial, and health challenges they had encountered, had overcome, and were still facing. Some victims, when it seemed appropri- ate, also were asked to comment on the activities of other victims whom they knew, had read about, or in other ways had heard about since Madoff was arrested. Forty-two individuals or couples responded favorably to the request to participate in this phase of the study, and an additional eight responded but declined to provide addi- tional information beyond what had already been gathered. Moreover, 14 of the 42 were interviewed, seven one time, four twice, and three thrice. Thirteen of the 167, along with 16 other individuals, contributed a brief memoir to a volume of essays, letters, and poems put together in 2010 by a group of Madoff victims and family members, and what the thirteen wrote was utilized to supplement information previously provided by them or otherwise collected for their files. As an interpretive framework, Erving Goffman’s observations about the social processes that come into play for placating those who have suffered a loss, who have been cheated or who may feel cheated or in other ways disappointed, are used. “On Cooling the Mark Out” In one of his highly original essays, “On Cooling the Mark Out,” Erving Goffman first turns his attention to crime and its victims, particularly those taken in by a “confidence man” (or woman or gang) and by their need to adjust to their loss—to the realization that they had actually been deceived and cheated. Of particular relevance, Goffman notes that “the con [the swindle] differs from politer forms of financial deceit in important ways. The con is practiced on private persons by talented actors who methodically and regularly build up informal social relationships just for the purpose of abusing them; white-collar crime is practiced on organizations by persons who learn to abuse positions of trust which they once filled faithfully. The one exploits poise; the other position.” It is immediately apparent why Goffman’s insights prove especially valuable in framing and understanding the information provided by Madoff’s victims about what they thought, felt, and did in the aftermath of experiencing their loss and disappointment. Since loss and disappointment are part of the human condition, the true significance of Goffman’s essay is, of course, that the themes he explores go far beyond those who have been cheated in a confidence game. His insights help further our understanding of those who have a grievance about any loss and disappointment. This would include those victimized because of their actions or because of the actions of others who also may have been taken in. Goffman contends that the con is “a good racket in the United States only because most Americans are willing, nay eager, to make easy money, and will engage in action that is L. S. Lewis (*) 17 Morningside Lane, Williamsville, NY 14221, USA e-mail: soclsl@buffalo.edu Soc (2011) 48:159–173 DOI 10.1007/s12115-010-9412-5 less than legal in order to do so. The typical play has typical phases. The potential sucker is first spotted and one member…arranges to make social contact with him. The confidence of the mark is won, and he is given an opportunity to invest his money in a gambling venture which he understands to be fixed in his favor. The venture, of course, is fixed, but not in his favor. The mark is permitted to win some money and then persuaded to invest more. There is an ‘accident’ or ‘mistake’ and the mark losses his total investment.” The Robert Redford-Paul Newman movie The Sting (inspired by real-life events) with all of these elements—the quest for easy money, the bait with the promise of a sure win, the ruse to gain trust, and the loss of everything due to a misunderstanding— portrays perfectly how a con works. Madoff’s Ponzi scheme, since it began sometime after the 1973 release of The Sting, might be looked at as life imitating art. Although as inventive, complex, and typical, it proved far less entertaining. Goffman also notes that sometimes a mark is not prepared to accept a loss, and may feel moved to complain to authorities. In order to avoid such adverse publicity, an additional phase “is sometimes added at the end of the play. It is called cooling the mark out.” Although the reaction of anyone who has been swindled is unpredictable, con men depend on their “grift sense” to tell them roughly what an individual’s reaction will be. Will he cry or complain? Will she do something ridiculous? Maurer has written that “some marks are tough and can cause plenty of trouble if they get out of hand. Some are well-bred and take their medicine like men. Laughing marks are usually considered the most dangerous…. Some marks are mean, grasping, and cunning.” “It is easy for the layman to understand,” Maurer adds, “why some marks blow up when they realize that they have been trimmed [cheated]. If these marks are not properly cooled out, they may get the mob into serious trouble….” At the same time, “many of them [marks], realizing or suspecting that they have been swindled, immediately cause trouble, and all the ingenuity and persuasiveness of the inside man is required to prevent serious repercussions; sometimes all that fails and the con men are indicted. But not very often, considering the large number of marks who are beaten.” To minimize repercussions, it is obviously worthwhile to make an effort to cool the mark out. However, besides the short court trial, where a handful of victims were briefly permitted to crush Madoff verbally and to listen to the sentencing judge do the same, this element was missing in the months following his arrest, when his victims were most unsettled. There was little to keep the anger of Madoff’s victims, the marks, “within manageable and sensible proportions.” In short, there was insufficient consolation and very obviously this exacerbated an already unacceptable situation. It would not have surprised Goffman that very few of Madoff’s victims were willing to accept their loss. Almost immediately, a number were busy challenging individuals and institutions which they believed were not sufficiently engaged in working on their behalf to overturn the damage caused by Madoff, and which fell short of adopting their world-view. As time passed, more joined their efforts. The majority who became active in pressing their case stayed active; in the first year the involvement of only a few flagged. From the beginning, the victims’ situation was untenable given that a number of those who had invested with Madoff were convinced that: (1) They were privy to inside information (Hadn’t a bridge partner or someone in their golf foursome told them their investment was a sure thing?); (2) They were entitled—a view that the successful careers of so many of them made plausible and readily acceptable; (3) They were smart, a belief so many middle class American hold about themselves; (4) They could not lose (after all, their cousin’s niece was building quite a nest egg with Madoff, and she was not yet 40 years old.); (5) They were deserving. In fact, an incredibly large number described themselves as “frugal” and “hard-working,” an assessment sometimes, but not always, borne out by their biographies: We lived simply, in an apartment while putting money aside to purchase a future home. Since I was not an earner, I contributed by taking on responsibilities that would have cost money. So I did all the housework, cleaning and polishing, washing and ironing, hem- ming and altering plus I gave up personal expenses like beauty parlors and bought only inexpensive clothing. We drove used cars, camping was the way we vacationed. I set up a tiny section of our bedroom for a studio and snatched little bits of time to paint. Also my sense of community responsibility, inherited from my parents, was always with me. School issues became a major concern and soon I became president of a very large, active PTA. I called a conference where we determined the books in elementary schools did not reflect the diversity of our city. As a result the books were rewritten. And we achieved that goal. That was just one of the many worthy projects to which I gave time. (Client #28) We didn’t live with millions of dollars. We lived with people like ourselves—middle class people who worked damned hard to earn a buck. (Client #123C) It is hardly surprising that some dropped their usual defenses which had heretofore protected them and their families from being victimized in matters small and large. As a result, all lost a significant amount of their savings; a 160 Soc (2011) 48:159–173 number reported they were left penniless or, as they saw it, nearly penniless. On top of this, they had no protection from media-fueled second guessing and ridicule from friends, acquaintances, and strangers. A few, but only a few, began to see what those who had not suffered a loss at the hands of Madoff saw, namely, that perhaps they were not as shrewd or smart as they had thought, but simply marks in a very large, long-running, and, for them, invisible con game. The situation was continually made much worse by the probing media, or from media which mindlessly echoed their self serving and sometimes erroneous claims while drowning out voices that might otherwise have helped cool them out. In fact, a small number seemed to be vying to see how often they could be interviewed by a television or newspaper reporter. (See Appendix for an example of a joint television interview of nine victims, seven of whom were from the initial list of 167, covering myriad issues.) They did not have, as they had convinced themselves, an inside track on safely and profitably invest- ing. Some, if not all, self images surely suffered. The absolute necessity that they be consoled, that they be “cooled out,” was immediately evident, but it rarely happened. After the swindle in The Sting, the mark is quickly hustled out of the fake betting parlor by a police officer, being told that it is better to lose a substantial amount of money than to become fodder to the press or even to become implicated in a double homicide. However, for Madoff’s victims there was no social mechanism, no representative of the law or government to perform this function. Some government agency might have done so, but none did. On the contrary, the staff of the SEC, which may have served this function, had with each passing week revealed how hapless and dysfunctional it had become. Moreover, the trustee who represented Madoff’s estate and the SIPC made a number of decisions with which most victims vehemently disagreed. On top of that, the courts supported the trustee’s interpretation of the law and his actions. Finally, the government sometimes seemed to go out of its way to wrong victims. Client #23 reports, for example: “We filed a claim with the IRS for a refund due to a theft loss and received a refund of $30,000 for a 5-year period which was great, but then they decided to audit us for the theft loss and said they want the money back until they can determine if the Madoff claims are truly a theft loss…. So we are working that out now…. The IRS believes that the money still exists (per our IRS agent information) and given that they are contesting most of the refund claims, we are told.” Goffman reminds us that it is a mistake in a con game to account for the greatness of anger by the greatness of financial loss: “In many cases, especially in America, the mark’s image of himself is built up on the belief that he is a pretty shrewd person when it comes to making deals and that he is not the sort of person who is taken in by anything. The mark’s readiness to participate in a sure thing is based on more than avarice; it is based on a feeling that he will now be able to prove to himself that he is the kind of person who can ‘turn a fast buck’.” At best, their loss and disappointment only proved to Madoff’s victims that they were no wiser than they were decades earlier, that they had not been taught or learned a great deal over the years. “Why should I suffer any loss?” Client #31A asked. “It might not seem like a lot, and I can earn it all and more back in less than 2 years, but it was mine and not Madoff’s to buy another house with.” Client #86 concurred: “It’s not the money, which is no big thing, but the principal (sic). It [the loss] isn’t going to make us change how and where we live, but I still intend to get every dollar back no matter how long it takes.” It is hardly surprising that not only were there few if any victims of Madoff who would share Goffman’s (or a career con man like “Yellow Kid” Weil’s) conclusion that some of them might have been a little too eager to make money and that was why in the end they lost it. Instead, many victims became infuriated at even the suggestion that they may have done anything which had contributed to their financial losses. When it was suggested to Client #97B that the victims not only did not want to take any responsibility for their financial losses, but believed in their complete innocence, he indignantly wrote: “You are completely clueless as to why we feel the way we do, and in many cases your description of the victims is so completely wrong and demonstrates your ignorance and misperceptions of the history of Madoff.” He, not unexpectedly, refused to participate further in the study. Actually, there were many as deeply hurt and suspicious after the loss of all or a large percentage of their economic security. (Client #97B, whose investment in the Ponzi scheme was largely from his professional earnings, “lost $3 million to Madoff.”) After such a searing experience, it is surprising that any were willing to participate in the study or be interviewed, although one journalist reported that “once word got out that I was going to write an article about the Madoff mess, my cell phone never stopped ringing. Victims I hardly knew wanted to tell their stories, vent their anger, get revenge.” Challenging the SIPC Even in light of the many bruised egos and small amount of help from government sources, the degree of suspicion about the motives of the public face of the federal government, the SIPC and the trustee, seemed excessive. In the expression of anger here nothing was out of bounds. Soc (2011) 48:159–173 161 In spite of the amount of time they spent, the economic and psychological costs incurred, and the complete lack of success in their efforts, the victims assaulted the trustee at every turn. The crux of the feud with the SIPC and the trustee was a disagreement about the meaning and interpretation of the Securities Investor Protection Act (SIPA) of 1970 (and its 1978 amendments). First, Madoff’s victims believed that they had insurance against losses. However, a court decision in 1975 ruled that the SIPC is not an insurer, nor does it guarantee that customers will recover their invest- ments which may have diminished as a result of, among other things, market fluctuations or broker-dealer fraud. This was the trustee’s position. Second, most of Madoff’s victims—those who invested directly with him and those who invested indirectly with him through a feeder fund— held that they were entitled to SIPC benefits. However, court decisions have held that Congress intended SIPA to protect only those who entrusted property directly to a broker, specifically. The only type of investor who qualified as a customer of a broker-dealer was an investor who paid cash directly to a broker-dealer. Indeed, one court decision pushes this definition further, stating that individuals who unwittingly invested in a Ponzi scheme by issuing checks payable to anyone other than to the failed broker, were not customers within the meaning of the SIPA. This was the trustee’s position. In a court filing, the SIPC held that to be truly a Madoff customer, an investor must have had a securities account with him or had cash or securities with him with the reasonable expectation that an account would be set up, and must have entrusted cash or securities for the purpose of investing in securities. This could only be “ascertainable from the books and records” of Madoff. Third, Madoff’s victims argued that their net equity was what they had invested with him. However, the courts interpreted net equity to mean total value of cash and securities “less total value of cash and securities” the customer owed to the broker. Thus, according to the courts, net equity can be easily determined by calculating what would have been owed the customer if securities had been liquidated. The reasoning was that because for Madoff’s victims there were no securities to be liquidated, accounts were valued according to what was invested minus what was withdrawn. This was the trustee’s position. Fourth, some Madoff victims believed they were entitled to interest on their investments. However, the courts ruled that the SIPA does not authorize the payment of interest on customer accounts. In fact, when a brokerage firm was operating a Ponzi scheme this did not include supposed interest that customers were to receive on their investments; rather, customers were entitled, subject to statutory limits, to only the return of their principal as reduced by any amount which they had received from brokerage, whether as interest, return of principal, or any other payment. This was the trustee’s position. Fifth—and what was surely the most contentious issue as far as the victims were concerned—was how the total amount of their investment should be determined. A large majority of the victims (at least those who expressed their view on the matter) believed that the value of their account could be found in the November 2008 statement from Madoff, the last one they received before his arrest. Yet, this was contrary to a 2004 court case, which held that claims of purchasers of bogus securities were required to be valued at the amount they initially paid for them, and could not include any artificial interest or dividend reinvestments reflected in fictitious account statements that may have been received. This was the trustee’s position. A number of victims who were not initially convinced that they had been wronged by the government’s take on one or more of these points of disagreement were shortly convinced otherwise by other victims—often by means of online websites (online communities, online networks, online social support groups), which mushroomed and thrived. Attorneys also were instrumental in persuading victims that the most effective way of forcing the trustee to reverse a position, that is, of “getting the complete justice they deserved,” was going on the attack not only against the trustee, but also his staff, and the SIPC. Among other things, they initiated lawsuits, complained to their elected representatives and the media, and wrote e-mails and letters. Victims also were urged to challenge the courts, which interpreted the law in the same way as the trustee. This was not an easy matter; yet they persisted. In their dispute with the trustee, the victims often spoke about fairness, principles, equity, justice, and the like. But it was quite evident that they were less moved by these concepts than by the wish to get as much of their investments returned to them as possible, and they expected—some demanded—prompt action. At bottom, many disputes were about money and little else: “I think the way we have been treated by everyone shows that most people today lack compassion…. I would think,” Client #72 argued, “every- one would agree that as a country we would all be better off if more of us practiced the ‘Golden Rule’…. That’s really what this country is about…. Yes, Congress and the president should see that we get all of our money back plus interest.” And again: “Does anyone not agree that we have been hurt by unfair treatment? And why is it that only those who play by the rules end up being hurt? ... I would hope that you would understand that if fair play wins out, our IRA and the IRAs of others will be fully restored…. Who wouldn’t want [their] money back?” The SIPA and the courts had given the trustee broad and nearly unassailable power, and it was clear it would not be easy to convince him to return any more to the victims than 162 Soc (2011) 48:159–173 he believed the law, as he interpreted it, said they had coming. He was unyielding, and not much interested in what he saw as peripheral issues. His firmness only incensed victims, who believed that he was unnecessarily unyielding. They were convinced that the questions they were raising were truly relevant and worth considering. They felt he too often ignored them. Not everyone, of course, was disappointed at the govern- ment’s response to their plight. When, for example, one of the nine individuals (Client #86) selected to denounce Madoff at his sentencing trial in June received his $500,000 check from the SIPC four months after he had submitted his claim, he was elated. Although Madoff had stolen $5 million from him and the government payment was only 10% of that amount, he understood that by law it was the maximum the government would reimburse any account and he considered himself “well off by any reasonable standard and for that I am grateful.” The money would be of immediate use to pay off the first mortgage on his home. He seemed particularly pleased that he was among the first claimants the SIPC paid. (A few other victims groused that his claim was readily settled because he had political connections. This unsubstantiated accusation found its way into the media.) He promptly returned his questionnaire and optimistically wrote: “Since I lost almost $5,000,000 by investing directly with Madoff and indirectly through two feeder funds and because the overall economy has experienced an extremely severe recession, naturally my financial situation has deteriorated. I still consider myself well off financially and certainly have no reason to complain when so many millions of people cannot find jobs…. I immediately [as he had averred he would] paid off the mortgage on our home. We also received considerable tax refunds from the federal government, but not from [the state in which he resides], which refuses to refund the taxes we paid on fictitious income.” It is noteworthy that at the time he received the $500,000 from the SIPC, 99 percent of the nearly 9,000 Madoff investor claims at that point had not even been approved. Nonetheless, few of Madoff’s victims would be as pleased by the SIPC’s action. And Client #101 understood that her “situation [was] probably a little different from” that of most of Madoff’s victims. She was younger than most and had two young children. A few months before Madoff was arrested, she was diagnosed with thyroid cancer and had a thyroidectomy, and after that she discovered that her husband was having an affair with her best friend. Still, after “losing all my money” she found employment and with the help from other friends and relatives, but none from the government, she reported that her “life is much better now than it was before the Madoff fiasco actually.” She concluded that she got “pleasure from [her] work…, [and that] I’m actually a very lucky person.” Both Clients #86 and 101 were clearly part of a tiny minority. More typically, an individual who had written a succinct and compelling victim impact statement (Client #143) promptly became the co-principal in a lawsuit against the trustee, claiming that he had treated her unfairly in adjudicating her claim. After an unfavorable court decision, she brought another action, but again she was unsuccessful. Her attorney, who herself had invested with Madoff, did not cool her out. On the contrary, she urged her not to back down, to continue to seek redress in the courts. The attorney, in fact, had written the court earlier demanding that victims “must be given a seat at the table. To date, we have not been given that opportunity…in the bankruptcy proceedings….” She went on to remind the court that “people in their 90’s are being put into nursing homes for the first time in their lives because their children can no longer afford to maintain them in private homes. People in their 70’s and 80’s, who retired with the assurance of a steady income from their Madoff accounts, are being forced to sell their houses in a depressed market in order to have money to buy food.…” She asked that the government become more active in finding the stolen funds, and that the court “appoint a committee of investors [to help] assure restitution to Madoff’s victims.” Given the rawness of the attorney’s emotions, it is hardly surprising that this client and any of her other clients were not prepared to accept their losses. Whatever the challenge, the trustee remained unmoved, and was certainly not prepared, himself, to cool victims out. Three irreversible decisions by the trustee, the SIPC, and its attorneys were centermost to this and to other victims’ bitterness. First, the trustee and the SIPC would not budge from the decision to pay its full $500,000 insurance obligation only on the amount investors actually invested with Madoff, less any withdrawals they may have made (that is, net investment), ignoring years of phantom profits on which taxes had been paid. The SIPC did not see the tax issue of some victims as a problem it needed to solve. Second, the trustee was determined to recover the money that investors may have withdrawn from their accounts that was in excess of their investment with Madoff. He had set in motion a plan to promptly move ahead on this matter. This was called a “clawback.” Third, he continued to insist that only funds directly invested with Madoff, and not those invested in feeder funds, were covered by SIPC. According to the aforementioned lawyer’s 2009 con- gressional testimony—and math—at about the time she was writing the court, these procedures established by the SIPC “would reduce the total Madoff claims from $64.8 billion to approximately $21 billion and…reduce the number of customers entitled to SIPC insurance from approximately 4,904 account holders to 2,335 account holders.” She also contended that the SIPC proposal that individuals “pay back to the bankruptcy estate all funds withdrawn within Soc (2011) 48:159–173 163 the past 6 years up to the amount of the negative net investment” was grossly unfair. What she and some of her clients actually wanted was to replace the trustee after he had denied “prompt replacement of up to $500,000 of … securities as reflected on their November 30, 2008 statement received from Madoff.” They were convinced that getting the court to remove the trustee was a first and necessary step that needed to be taken if they were to have any success in their efforts to be made financially whole. The trustee and the SIPC had argued in court that returning the amount clients found in their November 2008 statements was completely “imprac- ticable,” as the statements reflected non-existent invest- ments and were, of course, complete fabrications. Much to the annoyance of Madoff’s victims, the attorney for the SIPC told the judge that “no one in their right mind” would use financial statements that were simply fabricated by Madoff as a basis for calculating assets: “The last customer statement, being a concoction of a fraudster, is not something on which you can rely” in calculating net equity. (When victims later learned that in just one four-month period this attorney submitted a bill to the court for $837,457.50, having worked 1,015.10 hours at $825 an hour, they could only be described as absolutely rabid.) The SIPC held firm that of the 15,870 claims that had been filed at that point only 2,336 were truly valid, as they were the only ones that had a net loss. This also further infuriated a number of Madoff’s victims. The SIPC was holding fast to the trustee’s method for compensating investors: “cash in/cash out.” In effect, with this decision, the trustee had reduced the SIPC’s liabilities from more than $7 billion (certainly not $64.8 billion) to approximate- ly $1.2 billion. (All of these numbers were constantly changing, and will continue to change before all matters are fully resolved over the years. At a later date, with more than 15,000 claims filed, the Madoff trustee Website valued the total number of “allowed claims” at roughly $5.2 billion.) The condescension and firmness on all matters by the SIPC legal team completely enraged the Madoff victims, who repeatedly challenged the trustee but with no success. They were prepared for a long and bitter fight, and this is exactly what they were in the midst of. The bankruptcy judge, although expressing sympathy for the defrauded investors, concurred with the SIPC trustee, writing “the account statements are entirely fictitious, do not reflect actual securities positions that could be liquidat- ed, and therefore cannot be relied upon to determine net equity.” He concluded that because securities were never “ordered, paid for, or acquired…the only verifiable amounts that are manifest from the books and records are the cash deposits and withdrawals.” The Madoff victims were not deterred. For her part, the attorney for the Madoff investors argued that the trustee’s actions were “solely to enrich SIPC at the expense of SIPC’s insureds.” She expressed the seemingly overlarge concern that “aside from the devastation Picard [the trustee] has caused to thousands of customers, he has created a serious threat to the national economy because he is single-handedly destroying investor confidence in the capital markets.” She was one of the first to suggest that at bottom the trustee was more interested in saving the SIPC money than in helping the victims recover their money. He was more concerned with minimizing the losses of brokers and bankers than those of investors. One victim referred to him as a “stooge.” Another victim described him as a “thief,” and “no better than a hired assassin.” Another victim called him a “pimp.” Another victim simply wondered why he was so calloused, so determined to use them as “pawns.” As this very much involved lawyer saw it, what the trustee had done was much more than unlawful; it was a “violation of the public trust.” In fact, however, the public was becoming less sure of this assessment. To the decreasing number of the public still paying attention, the tactics of the victims were beginning to look “desperate” and “greedy.” (Although his victims had largely lost interest in Madoff after he was found guilty and imprisoned, the public, fascinated by the grandness of his Ponzi scheme, was still very much interested in every detail of his life in prison fed to them by the media. Like Princess Diana, O.J. Simpson, Natalee Holloway, or Nelson Mandela, Madoff had become a bona fide celebrity.) In the eyes of many of Madoff’s investors, the effect of the totality of the SIPC’s decisions was to victimize them yet once again. This became an idée fixe. The Trustee Very quickly, and not surprisingly, the trustee became the primary target of the victims’ considerable and continually growing anger. His actions had done little to cool them out. At the same time, the trustee soon became the only face of the government. The widespread view in government circles was that those whose money had been stolen by Madoff were surely unfortunate, but not deserving of extraordinary help, not deserving of a government rescue, or, as some elected representatives and those in the media put it, “a bailout.” The trustee apparently also held this view. As they continued to question and pummel the trustee on every point, as they continued to press their case, the victims came to be seen more and more by outsiders as simply greedy. The reservoir of sympathy for them had begun to evaporate more and more rapidly. At this point, at least publicly, the trustee appeared to be very much concerned about the plight of the victims, yet there was absolutely no hope of his adopting any points they were so keen in making, let alone their world-view. As he saw it, his responsibility was straightforward: His job 164 Soc (2011) 48:159–173 was to collect as many of the assets that Madoff had not spent or that had not inexplicably vanished and distribute them fairly to those whose money had been lost in the Ponzi scheme. He continued to argue that his “cash in/cash out approach to calculating ‘net equity’ is the only one consistent with SIPA [law], bankruptcy law, principles of equity, and common sense.” The trustee was aware that there would be many challenges to the method being used to determine claims. In fact, by March 31, 2010, over 2,600 objections had been filed with the Bankruptcy Court. Some victims continued to insist that the cash in/cash out approach was arbitrary and unfair, that the value of a claim should be based on their November 30, 2008 statement; some still wanted interest paid on their investment; some believed that they were entitled to an immediate payment of $500,000; some argued that indirect investors, not only direct investors, should be covered by the SIPC; some contended that each name on a joint account should be eligible for an SIPC payment. The trustee was besieged on all sides. Not once did he waver. Regardless of their lack of success in court against the trustee, some victims were undeterred in their efforts to thwart his efforts to move ahead. At times the court grew impatient with their unwillingness to accept the fact that they had been swindled, and to quit contesting each step in the process of collecting and redistributing what Madoff had accumulated. When, for example, after losing a decision, a plaintiff filed again, “raising virtually the identical issues,” the exasperated judge concluded that the entire exercise was “bordering on [the] frivolous.” The trustee found most allegations against him to be “spurious,” but was decidedly bothered by the fierce ad hominem attacks against him and the SIPC staff. He seemed truly surprised by how many were suspicious of every action he took. By tying him up in legal minutiae, the victims were slowing his work of cleaning up the mess Madoff had left behind. Of course, the longer he was required to stay on the job, the more he earned as trustee. What he was doing may at times have hurt him personally, but it was surely lucrative, thanks in part to the victims’ activism. At times, Madoff’s victims were uncharacteristically quiet when the trustee resolved a complicated matter. They were silent, for example, when in late August 2010 he convinced the judge overseeing Madoff’s business affairs to ask the Supreme Court of Gibraltar to transfer $73.1 million to him to use to compensate those who had lost money in Madoff’s Ponzi scheme. And Suing the Trustee On the other hand, about a week after this trustee success, a number of victims joined two lawsuits challenging a nearly $34 million bill for work the trustee and his firm had performed in the previous quarter, from February 1, 2010 through May 31, 2010. In the first suit, the plaintiffs reminded the court that “this equates to $5,010 in daily compensation, including all weekends and holidays, for the trustee, and $283,179.45 in daily compensation for [his law firm], again including all weekends and holidays…. These figures are excessive by any measure and should not be approved….” The core of one suit was that “investors have no ability to evaluate the efficiency or professionalism of the work” because “detailed billing reports” were not filed. The contention was that these eye-popping fees “come directly from SIPC—from the very money that is necessary to pay investors the $500,000 in SIPC insurance to which they are entitled under SIPA.” The second suit alleged that “the trustee has failed to disclose material information,” information “vital for customers to know and yet it has been concealed from customers and the public”; and that “the trustee and [his law firm] have a conflict of interest” in that the trustee and his law firm “are far from ‘disinterested’”: as a result of which “they are barred from receiving any compensation under established precedents and principles of professional conduct.” In a 47-page response, the attorney for the trustee not unexpectedly restated that “the trustee and his counsel continued to work diligently on behalf of customers” and Madoff’s estate. He also repeated that “no administrative costs…will be paid out of any recoveries obtained by the trustee for the benefit” of Madoff’s clients. The filing also summarized the trustee’s professional background and services. The trustee was still proceeding very deliberately. (As of August 13, 2010, the trustee had determined 13,286 customer claims, of which 2,188 were allowed, and had committed to pay approximately $715 million in funds advanced to him by the SIPC. The allowed claims totaled over $5.5 billion.) Only weeks earlier the trustee had issued a report detailing his activities, and here he was compelled again to make the case that his efforts were unflagging. He attempted to quiet his critics by pointing out that he had gathered and organized approximately seven thousand boxes of paper documents, identified approximately 8.3 million pages of documents to scan, was working to assess the contents of more than 4,000 reels of microfilm and 87 transfile boxes of microfiche. He had also accumulated and stored 1.4 million e-mails. Yet at this point, his staff was still able to review 12,249 claims, of which 2,011 were allowed for a total of $5.3 billion, and he had committed to pay $668 million in cash advances from the SIPC. For the most part, he denied the other 10,238 claims either because those accounts had withdrawn more money than had been deposited or the claim was filed by someone who was not a Soc (2011) 48:159–173 165 direct investor with Madoff. At the same time, the trustee had recovered $1.5 billion and had filed fourteen avoidance actions seeking to recover more than $14.8 billion in principal and fictitious profits from various feeder funds, Madoff family members and friends, and related parties. He had also issued subpoenas to more than 600 parties and received approximately 6 million documents. If nothing else, his office was extremely busy, and was kept busier by the constant assaults on it by Madoff’s victims. Victims held him up with legal maneuvers, and then wondered why his work did not progress more rapidly and why it had become so costly. Nearly 16 months after Madoff’s arrest, only 1,769 accounts out of 16,314 claims had been fully or partially satisfied. Of the claims, 4,273 were under review and 7,865 were denied, for which no objections were filed. These figures were at the core of the agitation of many of Madoff’s victims and their supporters, family, friends, attorneys, and journalists who had a public forum: The Securities Investor Protection Corp., (SIPC) whose logo brokerage firms pay to print on their statements to gin up a sense of security among retail customers, has not paid back the bulk of Madoff investors, although the agency was set up under the Nixon administration for the express purpose of protecting Americans who tangle with Wall Street. In a strangely twisted view, SIPC is actually proud to have not helped investors who are victims of Wall Street fraud, including Madoff investors. Is the SIPC logo on your brokerage statement? Probably. Don’t expect any money back, even when it’s been stolen from you outright. A number of victims joined in the outcry. Client #97A confessed to being overwhelmed by “rage against [the] injustice” she confronted at the hands of SIPC: None of the victims are “winners.” We are all losers. The only winners in the debacle are [the trustee] and his law firm who have been making over a million dollars a week for over a year now. To imply that any of us are winners is disgusting…. We feel it’s immoral to again victimize people who lost their life savings by demanding back money they withdrew in good faith and which they believed was theirs. Elderly people are being tortured by the threat of clawbacks, fearing the little they have left and their homes will be taken from them. Mr. Madoff isn’t deciding who is entitled to restitu- tion. Mr. Picard [the trustee] and Mr. Harbeck [also from SIPC] are. They have used that absurd statement to deflect attention from their failure to adhere to SIPA legislation. They are not working for the victims. Their goal is to limit SIPC’s financial exposure and hence that of the securities industry. They claim that by using their calculations more victims will be helped. This is simply not true…. Their claim that SIPC is not insurance is a smoke screen. SIPC…might not have the word “insurance” in its name as FDIC…does…. SIPC is insurance. The only ones they are being “fair and equitable” to is [sic] the securities industry that pays their salaries. A relative, Client #97(B), added: While our “job” was to get the message out that Madoff was now irrelevant to us, and why SIPC, perverting the laws, was relevant to everyone. If SIPC could do this to us, they could do it to anyone…. The real tragedy was that the SIPC agency created by Congress to protect investors had instead turned against investors in favor of the securities industry it was beholden to…. SIPC has shown that they will not honor their statutory commitments. In an essay in the same volume, Client #123 wrote: But at 9,000 claims, poor old SIPC realized it would be out of money and probably existence if it honored its promises. SIPC’s definitions about responsibility were quickly rewritten. Investors who, by SIPC’s stated position, had a reasonable expectation to believe securities they were told were purchased on their behalf actually existed, were no longer entitled to have those securities restored to them nor the equivalent value of those securities in cash if the securities were no longer available…. The law firm denying those claims, in the meantime, is billing SIPC close to a million dollars a week, money that’s coming right out of the pot to reimburse investors. Client #125 had as many suspicions, referring to “the sham of SIPC.” Now the skirmish had escalated into a battle. The trustee, and, in effect, the SIPC were not simply being challenged and harassed by Madoff’s victims; they were being taken to court by them. There was the indignity of precisely describing all of the services rendered, of providing “a more detailed synopsis” task by task. The trustee even complained publicly that he and his attorneys had to spend time fighting repeated legal challenges by a handful of victims who “purport to represent a class of those similarly situated.” Moreover, the trustee’s attorney faced the additional indignity of submitting an affidavit certifying that the application for compensation “complies with guidelines for fee application” under bankruptcy law, and even that in seeking reimbursement for services purchased 166 Soc (2011) 48:159–173 or contracted from a third party it requested money “only for the amount billed.” Less than 2 weeks after the two lawsuits were filed against the trustee, the bankruptcy judge awarded him the fees he had requested. This was the third time the judge had rejected victims’ objections in approving legal fees requested by the trustee. The effects of the actions on the part of Madoff’s victims on making the trustee’s work less lucrative may have been insignificant; however, they surely made it less pleasant, forcing him to publicly defend himself, his ethics and competence, and entreat the court for his money. Suing the SEC Six weeks after the SEC issued its self critical report, two of the victims of Madoff’s Ponzi scheme—a disabled, retired single mother and a physician approaching retirement— filed a lawsuit against the federal government accusing the SEC of negligence for failing to protect investors. The suit asked for monetary damages “arising from the serial, gross negligence … [during the SEC’s] multiple investigations and examinations.” Instead, by its implied clean bills of health or seal of approval, the SEC “caused Madoff’s scheme to continue, perpetuate, and expand in billions in losses by investors.” The two plaintiffs argued that Madoff could have and should have readily been stopped. The premise of the lawsuit was that the SEC was responsible to Madoff’s investors as it is reasonable to expect that they would rely on the SEC to remove risk if it had information that he was engaged in illegal activity. Although it was Madoff’s dishonesty that was responsible for their losses, the SEC’s actions and inactions, the plaintiffs contended, were a substantial factor in bringing about their injuries. It had not “carried out its functions with even a minimum of reasonable care,” and it showed a “wanton” indifference to public safety. The SEC had an obligation to examine and investigate “potential wrongdo- ing within the context of defined policies and routine common sense practices.” However, in spite of multiple complaints and investigations, as well as the several reviews or inquiries, it had failed to do so. The SEC, the plaintiffs further argued, disregarded its policy that all relevant information from complaints be vetted. This was due to at least one of the following: negligence, incompetence, inexperience, inattentiveness, or laziness. Moreover, it was acknowledged that policies and practices in place for “case opening and closing memoran- da, investigation planning memoranda, and communica- tions between SEC offices and teams” were “routinely disregarded.” Of particular relevance, in its inquiries the SEC failed not only to confirm Madoff’s claimed trading activities, it disregarded pertinent information because of inter-office rivalries, and although it caught Madoff repeatedly in contradictions and inconsistencies, failed to validate or ask him to validate his claims. For example, during the course of one investigation, SEC staff members knew that what he told them about his management of hedge funds and overseas accounts; the reason customer statements were so vague about trading details; and that he did not use e-mail to communicate with clients were all untrue, but they nonetheless continued to rely on his oral representations. He was most obviously lying when he first claimed large scale option trading that was patently non- existent and later when he reported that he had stopped using such options. These assertions were purported to be central to his claim of why his investment strategy was consistently successful. The SEC did not appear bothered by the barrage of Madoff’s untruths, perhaps assuming such behavior was generally expected from the financial organ- izations it monitored. Or it might have been that some of the time its staff members were simply not paying attention. The government attorneys responded that the SEC’s failure to curtail Madoff’s fraud was due to “discretionary judgments” and as a consequence shielded from liability. Quite simply, this means that even if one were to characterize the investigative work of the SEC as incom- petent or negligent, the government cannot be sued, unless it agrees to be sued, “based upon the exercise or performance or the failure to exercise or perform a discretionary function or duty.” The government’s defense was that the law gives it blanket immunity when the judgments of its officials are in question. A Touch of Greed and Fragile Egos As Goffman reminds us, before any con is initiated, one is most likely to find evidence of greed and after any con is executed one is more likely to find a plenitude of bruised egos. With the Madoff Ponzi scheme both greed and bruised egos were much in evidence. First, in an effort to maximize the annual return on their savings, when pressed on the question, some individuals acknowledged investing a larger percentage of their wealth or too much of it with Madoff than proved to be prudent. More tellingly, some took out an additional mortgage on their home so that they could invest more money in their Madoff account. The contention of victim after victim was that a consistent return of between 8 and 12 percent is what one would expect from any investment, and that they did not find the returns offered by Madoff exceptional. However, if they truly believed this, it is unlikely that any of them would have cashed in all or most of their other investments and borrowed on their homes to increase the Soc (2011) 48:159–173 167 amount in their Madoff account. Yet: (1) One victim (Client #42A) lost his condominium valued at over $1 million because he could no longer afford to make the mortgage, insurance, and maintenance payments. A few years earlier, he had borrowed against it in order to increase the total in his account with Madoff. He blamed his plight on inaction by the government. “Why shouldn’t we be fully reimbursed by a government program?” he wondered. “It should be like Social Security and Medicare.” (2) A second victim (Client #126) was no less inclined to blame the government for her decision to completely trust Madoff: “Upon my retirement, I cashed my pension, 401K, and additional salary that I received. I added all of this to my Madoff IRA.” As she too saw it, the government was making the situation a great deal worse: “Only a morally bankrupt society would keep taxes collected as a result of a criminal activity.” (3) A third victim (Client #147) was simply following what she believed were more knowledgeable relatives: “Slowly in 2003 and the early part of 2004, I liquidated all my holdings from Vanguard and transferred all of it over to Bernie’s able hands…. By 2004 I was fully invested with Madoff. I did have a small amount of bonds that I did not add to the pile of monies transferred. In the spring of 2003, I had decided to renovate my small but comfortable Florida condo that was completely paid for; the advice given me by the sage uncle and another financial advisor was to take a ‘little extra’ out in a loan and move it over to Bernie. ‘Don’t tie your money up in bricks and stone; have it out there working for you. You’ll earn more with Bernie than the bank will charge you in interest.’ So, I did just that and started making monthly mortgage payments. I now only owned part of my Florida home, and had also obtained a mortgage to purchase my Pennsylvania home. When it came time for a new car, my advice was not to take a large sum out of my investments with Bernard Madoff, but to get a loan, and make monthly statements. My rate on the bank loan will be less than the money I can earn with Madoff…. When each of my bonds matured, the advice I received was to either live on the money or ‘slide it over to Bernard Madoff.’” (4) Another victim, who had borrowed to invest with Madoff, asserted that he should be able to write off his bad debt. “Everyone cheats,” he complained, “and I’m just not going to be left holding the bag, whatever it takes.” (5) Client #69A detailed her roller coaster ride: “We lived short of our income for 34 years!! Just to be sure everything went into our investments. We did very well with our real estate and sold it all to roll it in to our accounts, then we sold our family home and rolled it in; my husband’s pension was rolled in as well as both of our IRAs; I was in a bad car accident and left with many injuries; I rolled my entire settlement into it also. Approximately 7 years ago, our investor decided to stop the annuity investing and other types that he did so we could ‘play with the big boys.’ He only wanted to make more money for all his retired clients.” (6) Like a number of others, Client #131, a retired businessman, claimed that he was simply following the advice of his accountant: “For many years I had all my investments with Merrill Lynch. I was getting a nice return on my money and was able to retire and live a comfortable life.” Apparently this was not enough, as “my accountant suggested I should diversify and recommended me to Madoff, telling me of his great returns on investments…. Eventually, because of his high rate of return I moved all of my money to an IRA account with Madoff.” For many of Madoff’s former clients the bruised egos and inevitable sadness were more evident than the greed. This was hardly unexpected. In fact, according to Goffman, the anger of the victims of a con has less to do with greed than with bruised egos. The fact that so few bruised egos had begun to heal a year and a half after Madoff’s arrest adds credence to Goffman’s conclusion. The material from the questionnaires and interviews indicates that four other factors often also fostered anger and sadness. First, the greater the proportion of their wealth individ- uals lost in the Ponzi scheme, the less likely their anger was to dissipate. With their material life in ruins, those who lost all or most of their money saw their future as bleak. The months and years ahead held little promise and there was little incentive to let go of anger and replace it with new plans or hope. These victims were not eagerly or optimis- tically looking forward to rebuilding their lives, but were more likely to be still focused on December 11, 2008, venting their anger publicly, hiring attorneys and listening to their advice, and blaming the government for their losses. It is hardly surprising that the greater the reduced circum- stances, the greater the anger and sadness. “I’ll never get over Madoff,” Client #55 assured me. “He’s wrecked my life. There’s no money left and no hope. I have nothing. I doubt if I’ll ever be happy again.” She added that one of her friends, someone who had lived close by, felt the same, and still had many sleepless nights and had become addicted to prescription medicines: “We were sure we were making careful decisions. I just don’t know how everything turned out so badly. It’s not easy to face each day with any confidence.” Second, the more individuals relied on other victims for information and emotional support, the angrier and sadder they were. To some, this might seem counter intuitive, but an examination of messages shared on the internet, where so many individuals went for information and support, suggests why this occurred. Although much necessary and useful information and good advice were shared on the internet, there was also a surfeit of misinformation and of 168 Soc (2011) 48:159–173 hostile interpretations of what had occurred, was occurring, and would occur, so that a poisonous atmosphere was pervasive. Unsubstantiated assertions were thrown about not only with little regard to their validity, but with little regard to their consequences. Rumors, speculation, and untruths, of course, did little to enhance understanding and dampen the still very raw passions of those in great pain. Too often, exchanges on the internet not only did nothing to cool the mark out, but instead caused a great deal of additional and unnecessary emotional turmoil. “I’ve heard more than one time,” client after client began a sentence before stating some outlandish claim: “The government doesn’t want to return our money, it wants to use it to fund a secret research project,” or “Madoff could only have done this with help from the highest levels of government.” Third, the more shabbily individuals believed they were treated by the government, the angrier or sadder, or angrier and sadder, they were. This was the case not only for those who actually appeared badly treated, ignored, or given the bureaucratic runaround. And it also included those who believed they were being treated badly because a decision or outcome proved to be unfavorable to their interests. It was relatively easy to convince the Ponzi scheme victims that government officials were not only uncaring, but set against them, determined to harm them even more. In a number of cases auditors for the Internal Revenue Service appeared to be decidedly unhelpful. Some elected officials gave the appearance of carefully listening to the entreaties of victims, but there is little evidence that they followed through with much action. Client #50’s experience is fairly typical: “As for the government, there has been no help whatsoever. I have written many letters to senators and congressmen and women. A very few answered with a standard form letter which really tells me a lot. I’m convinced most don’t care one iota. Most didn’t even have the decency to reply or acknowledge in any way.” Fourth, the greater the number of other setbacks, for example, health problems, family problems, or other financial problems—in addition to their financial losses due to investing with Madoff—the angrier and sadder they remained. It is obviously more difficult to bounce back from simply losing one’s savings in Madoff’s Ponzi scheme than from losing one’s savings and losing one’s spouse to alcoholism or divorce in a very short period of time. There is no way, of course, to know what the roots of the anger and sadness of Madoff’s victims were. All that can be said is that they were very apparent, and were not in the least dissipated by activism—writing letters or essays, broadcasting grievances, suing or the like. In a number of instances, in fact, activism appeared to enhance anger and sadness. Some might conclude that given the facts and the harm caused by Madoff’s Ponzi scheme, the levels of anger and sadness were not at all inappropriate, while others might disagree. It is important that while some caught up in Madoff’s Ponzi scheme appeared to be angry, angry and sad, or sad; others did not appear to be the least bit emotionally affected, not angry or not sad. It can be said, however, that anger had become an acceptable tenet of their world, very pervasive. As Goffman and any practiced con man surely would have concluded, there would have been less anger, grief, pain, or sadness if there had been someone, some mechanism or institution to cool the marks out. The sample of quotations from the forty-two files shed light on a great deal more than anger, grief, pain, sadness, or the general state of mind of these Madoff victims a year after he was sentenced to prison, but, more importantly, they shed light on how they were coping with their losses, financial and otherwise, as they waited for justice. The first point to be made here, however, is that some, almost one in five of the 42 respondents, expressed the belief that although their financial loss was a great personal disappointment that resulted in disrupting their lives significantly, they were reasonably pleased with how their lives had gotten back on track. Client #102: “My family and I were very fortunate insofar as we received our original stakes back from SIPC and, also, our capital gains taxes from the IRS. Moreover, we did not, by any means, have all our eggs in one basket (diversification!!!). There was, of course, shock initially and a certain amount of uncertainty until everything was worked out, which took a little more than a year…. The internet and, in particular, a private victims’ website, were invaluable in keeping up with developments, getting information, and sorting things out in my own mind…. Finally, I believe that [the trustee’s] definition of net equity is absolutely correct, as is his interpretation of SIPA. Thus, I harbor no anger and no grievance against him or anyone else. I blame myself (but only a bit) for being a gullible victim and for not being as smart as [the whistleblower] Harry Markopolos….” Another victim whose distress was substantially and relatively quickly eased was Client #131, whose congres- sional testimony, excerpted in a previous essay, details his losses. “At first,” he writes, “the realities of my finances were too much to bear. I was completely wiped out. Absolutely devastated financially; left with no money and few assets. Even after appearing before Congress I had no idea how bad my situation was and how much worse it would get…. To say it was difficult for my wife…and me would be an understatement. We were both in a terrible state of depression, and both undergoing psychological counseling. I have to say there was more than one time I thought about suicide.” However, Client #131’s life turned around fairly rapidly. Friends raised $50,000 to help pay the mortgage of his Soc (2011) 48:159–173 169 home; his son and daughter-in-law gave him $25,000; his sister, brother-in-law, sister-in-law, and nephews gave him more money; and his daughter and son-in-law bought him a house. In spite of the fact that his life is clearly materially better, he has not been entirely cooled out. Even after his financial recovery, he was still publicly blaming the SEC for what had occurred: “I could not believe the government would let a thing like this happen.” A second important point is that a considerable amount of grief or pain that the victims had initially felt had dissipated for many, but not for all. Client #106, who initially “almost killed himself,” who “barely made it through each day [because] I was so depressed and frightened,” would only go as far as to say that he was “not comfortable” answering questions such as whether the practice of his “old meditation techniques… from having another panic attack” had worked or were working. On the other hand, the outcome for Client #93, who described the weeks following Madoff’s arrest as a period marked by “a terrible depression—I did not drive a car for 3 weeks…. I contemplated suicide often and was put on heavy anti-depression medicine”—was clearly better. After a brief period, he wrote, “I was finally not suicidal and decided to do what I could to try to reinvent my life.” Client #131 admitted that he and his wife “both were in a terrible state of depression, and both undergoing psychological counseling,” and added, “I have to say there was more than one time I thought about suicide.” However, with the passage of time and with considerable financial help from family and friends, he and his wife “are the two happiest people in the world.” A word of caution: It is important not to exaggerate the victims’ greed. They entrusted their money to professional financial advisers, their decisions were supported by family and friends, and government oversight completely failed. It was a perfect storm. Many Americans expect the govern- ment to make them whole after a natural disaster. Many Americans expect the government to help them find new employment after they have lost their jobs in an economic downturn. It is hardly surprising that Madoff’s victims would expect government help. The investors most involved in efforts to recover what they had lost, particularly those using the media and the courts to press their case, were in almost every instance those most unwilling to acknowledge that they had been victimized. They were those who most behaved like victims—believing that those who had not shared their fate were not only uncaring and lacked empathy—but had the most difficulty coming to terms with the fact that they had, indeed, been victimized. They needed comfort; they had little need for understanding. They turned to others who also needed comfort. They professed their goodness—their penchant for hard work, their frugality, and their generosity. They were the first to turn on the government and to belittle government officials. They often claimed that those who were making efforts to assist them were not expending enough effort on their behalf. They most likely listened to the advice of attorneys regardless of how questionable it appeared to be. When asked about this assessment, one activist (Client #146) unhesitatingly shot back: “Sure I’m bitter. You would be too. And I’ll continue to be even if every cent is returned. I shouldn’t have had to beg for it. It’s mine, after all. How would you feel? Someone should have come to me; that would have been fairer.” Client #66, while expressing no bitterness, wondered why “everyone took so much enjoyment in piling on…. Before this happened I would do everything for anyone even before looking at my own needs.” And she asked: “I wonder where everybody is today?” Client #128(C) wrote: “I had felt very depressed for many, many months. It was hard to accept such losses. I felt that I had lost my identity, along with my self-respect. People judge you by what material things you have in your possession, your lifestyle, your money, and that is how they determine your status in the world. I felt crushed and anonymous, as if I had become transparent, and just didn’t count anymore.” His wife (Client #124(C)) wrote to the court about her “fear and anxiety,” “major depression” daily, and, elsewhere, about how she “thought that suicide was the only answer to stopping the pain.” Although their distrust of others did not appear to be greater than that of victims who were more likely to accept their new circumstances, they were generally more unfor- giving. They were clearly among the most rigid of the victims, but there is no way of ascertaining if this was characteristic of them before they had lost their savings to Madoff. A number were very self involved. It would seem their victimization had not only unsettled them financially, but it had badly bruised self images. Absence of Government Assistance Most victims not only did not receive concrete help from the government, but they could not even get government representatives to respond to their questions or appeals. Writing to the court in 2009, Client #126(C) seemed inconsolable: “It is our money he [Madoff] is using to continue to benefit himself. I am broke—robbed by the Madoff gang.” A year later only the focus, not the extent of her anger, had changed: “I spend hours each week on the phone with legislators in an attempt to recover the major source of monies available to me—taxes paid for two decades of fraudulent 1099 income.” Additional Setbacks Along with multiplying financial problems, a number of victims report health problems overwhelming them or their 170 Soc (2011) 48:159–173 spouse or both. There is no way, of course, of generally ascertaining how much their being victims of Madoff’s Ponzi scheme contributed to acute or chronic health problems, but in some cases a connection seems very obvious. Client #23: “Oh that [“your health”] is a big one…. You sure you want to ask?... Well I am at the age of a woman’s change and my body was already going through a lot and then with the added stress it went into a tailspin…. I was diagnosed with melanoma 9 months later and 13 months later had a severe reaction to environmental toxins (immune system down) and basically had to live in a bubble for 6 months and try to heal (which I am, yeah….) and then after 15 months [of pain] in my lower back that had me in bed for 2 months…. So now I am 1 month into a fairly healed body and have a whole new appreciation and lust for life…. I realized I was holding so much stress inside of me and emotions that it really almost took me out…. I had always dealt with challenges and life traumas before so I was damned if I was going to be a victim…. I had to be a survivor…. My husband was awesome but he became really sick about 6 months ago due to the stress…. He was just always there for me listening to me cry, listening to my anger [to] help and encourage me to go back to my old job…. He always offered to help with whatever needed to be done but it took its toll.” Client #50: “My health is very poor and has been going downhill with worry, frustration, and fear as I will pay for my last few months of surgeries, medical expenses, and chemo therapy, which I am about to start. I tell myself, though I’m certainly not ready to do so, that it would be easier if I just died. At least then I could leave something to my two remaining sons, of which we had five…. The last 2 years I have been unable to pay for this [an insurance policy] and I will probably have to give it up, losing all those years of very high premiums, leaving them with nothing but my home, which is modest and which I can no longer afford to keep up as it should be and always was. Is it any wonder my health has declined?” Client #69(A): “Our home went into foreclosure. My husband began drinking heavily and we are now in the process of getting divorced…. After losing everything I ended up breaking everything in my ankle and leg while hunting because we need meat for the winter. The following winter my husband fell off a ladder breaking his back while trying to remove large icicles off the edge of our roof because we couldn’t afford snow removal any longer for the valleys of our roof. My fibromyalgia and chronic fatigue syndrome increased immensely and now I have developed neuropathy in my hands and feet and have a lot of pain from my bionic ankle. I can’t get the medical help I really need due to [the] shortage of money. Some of the drugs I was on are not covered by Medicare and too expensive for me. My ex-husband is quite ill but continues to plow through working.” In answer to the question, “have things turned out better, about the same, or worse…?” she responded: “Worse because of the divorce after 36 years. I’m living on $2,000 per month and am disabled. I can’t afford the medications I need. If there is any recovery I’m told our portion would be $80,000 in 3–5 years. But we have so many attorneys working on it as a group that I’m sure they’ll end up with it all. By then I’ll be 70 and probably will have passed on. I can barely afford my little pet…. Both of us didn’t have our annual exam this year. We spent it on existing medical bills.” Client #125(C) writing on behalf of her elderly parents, both children of immigrants, told of their myriad illnesses, including heart disease, diabetes, kidney dis- ease, hip fractures, and hypertension, all made worse “by the stress induced by the loss of all their money.” Since Madoff’s arrest her father suffered a heart attack and a stroke and her mother is being treated for depression, while both “parents are scared and nervous every single day.” The daughter’s observation, that because of Madoff her parent’s “lives have become circumscribed,” is clearly an understatement. Client #88: “My life was shattered in 2008, first with the loss of my dear sister and her husband in October. My loyal canine companion …died. Then on December 11, 2008, I received a call…about my retirement money. I can hardly explain how this affected me, rage, depression, fighting with my husband…. My mental health was at a breakdown, I could not leave the house, I cried constantly. I had to be under a doctor’s care. I never felt as violated as I did that day when the call came. Then I was hearing that it would be years before this could be sorted out, hiring a lawyer, costly, useless…. I was completely obsessed with all things Madoff, writing letters, calling people who I thought might be able to assist me. [I spent much time] writing to [the judge], filing my forms with [the trustee], along with filing forms for hardship and SIPC assistance. Each reply I received did not offer up much consolation. Then in February 2009 I felt a lump in my right breast [and] I was diagnosed in March 2009 as Stage 2 then upgraded to Stage 3 breast cancer. Through 2009 I underwent chemo, went bald, felt near death, underwent a right breast mastectomy along with regular and oral radiation from March 2009 until now [late July 2010]. I am still looking at more surgery. My financial situation has been a nightmare…. I lost an investment property at no profit because of the economic climate. ([It] nearly was foreclosed on.) No one in the banking industry wanted to help out with a hardship loan situation. There was no one to help us, we felt abandoned by our government and still do. I have received no help from my government despite folders full of letters to the Soc (2011) 48:159–173 171 president, senators, congressmen and women…. I would like to have an official e-mail to where my experiences are headed. I failed also to tell you that my husband who is 72 has ESLS (end stage liver disease). I am 63 with breast cancer. We want our money back…. We all suffered and still do suffer under the Madoff fraud.” It should be added that some months earlier Client #88 had written: “The devastation that Bernard Madoff has brought into my life has erased all thoughts of man being inherently good.” The Greeks taught us that when we believe we are better than our fates a bitter ending is inevitable. The Madoff drama had a one-man Greek chorus, Harry Markopolos, warning all who would listen that there was not going to be a happy ending. Appendix: Nine Victims Speak on TV after Madoff Sentencing “What did you feel when he said, ‘I’m sorry for what I did?’” “I didn’t believe it.” “I think he’s sorry he got caught.” “I didn’t believe it when he said he was sorry.” “I didn’t believe it, because he has to say he’s sorry.” “When he stood up and put his hands behind his back and got handcuffed, I felt about 5 seconds of joy.” “[X], when you heard that he was remanded, that his bail was revoked, did that give you any sense of satisfaction that he would not go back to that penthouse on the Upper East Side and that he was going straight to jail?” “It’s not going to make me any wealthier how he gets punished, but in thinking about the situation, I think that he thinks he’s getting away with murder if he’s the only one who’s gonna go to jail in his family.” “We are in our own jails right now because of his actions.” “So that he’s in jail on one hand is, yes, he belongs there, but we need to try to help ourselves get out of our jail now.” “We’re just at the very beginning of untangling the legal, financial, and taxation web that he’s left behind.” “Can you tell us how your life has changed since December 11th [2008]?” “December 11th, the same day he turned himself in, we had sent in a check to buy a condo in an active-retirement community, and then the news broke.” “Now we’re worrying about having to pay the bills, from never thinking twice about it—if we wanted something, we could get it.” “My family members are in dire straits.” “My aunt and uncle in South Florida are in their 80s.” “They’re quite ill.” “They have been turned down for food stamps because their Social Security is too high.” “We no longer spend any discretionary expenses.” “That’s gone.” “But the bills keep coming in.” “And now I have to sell—we have to sell—our apartment in this market.” “I have no income coming in.” “I’ve had to move in with a parent.” “My apartment is up for sale in Florida and, as you know, at 52 years old, to have to move back….” “You all have told me—or the majority—you believe there is a misconception out there about the Madoff victims. Tell our viewers what that misconception is.” “The perception is that they’re just wealthy, greedy people.” “It’s not true.” “We’ve got professional people—doctors, lawyers, bankers—and we also have blue collar workers.” “Plumbers.” “Exactly, those unions.” “And we’ve got, you know, interior decorators.” “We’ve got people who are self-employed.” “We’ve got a lot of teachers, people who just had their life savings.” “Not huge amounts, but it was theirs.” “Is there a lesson here that you’d like to share with anyone?” “Basically, your question is: What could we have done differently?” “And you look back, and you say you really can’t.” “I looked at the SIPC stamp on the reports.” “My parents had been in it for 20 years.” “I mean, most times when there’s a fraud, everybody knows; it comes out fairly quickly.” “The money—the guy disappears; he runs away.” “That wasn’t the case here.” “This was long-standing, supposedly a successful firm blessed by the SEC.” “Do you blame [the SEC] most?” “Absolutely.” “Yes.” “Absolutely.” “This is what they’re commissioned to do, and how do [you] expect them to find any fraud if they cannot find the biggest, most blatant fraud that there is?”“If he was sitting where I am right now, what would you say to Mr. Madoff?” “What happened?” “How did you think that you were gonna keep doing this, and did you ever stop to think about the ramifications and what you’ve done to so many thousands of people?” This exchange fairly accurately captures the thinking of most Madoff victims in the months following his sentencing. Most striking is how decisive they were in apportioning blame 172 Soc (2011) 48:159–173 to others, and how certain they were that nothing they might have done would have prevented them from being harmed so gravely by Madoff. Their attention had quickly turned from themselves, and, in fact, from Madoff, to the government which had abetted him, which made his crime possible. They had granted themselves sufficient moral authority and had positioned themselves to ask that the government take extraordinary steps to make them whole. While their campaign was gaining focus and momentum, the public was growing indifferent, having steadily lost interest in the matter once Madoff was in prison. Lionel S. Lewis (A.B., Washington University; M.A., Cornell University; Ph.D., Yale University) is professor emeritus of sociology, SUNY/Buffalo. He is the author of 5 books and the author or co- author of 130 research articles, essays, and reviews, a number published in SOCIETY. This article is the fourth and final one in a planned series on the Madoff Ponzi scheme. Soc (2011) 48:159–173 173 After Madoff: Waiting for Justice “On Cooling the Mark Out” Challenging the SIPC The Trustee And Suing the Trustee Suing the SEC A Touch of Greed and Fragile Egos Absence of Government Assistance Additional Setbacks Appendix: Nine Victims Speak on TV after Madoff Sentencing << /ASCII85EncodePages false /AllowTransparency false /AutoPositionEPSFiles true /AutoRotatePages /None /Binding /Left /CalGrayProfile (Gray Gamma 2.2) /CalRGBProfile (sRGB IEC61966-2.1) /CalCMYKProfile (ISO Coated v2 300% \050ECI\051) /sRGBProfile (sRGB IEC61966-2.1) /CannotEmbedFontPolicy /Error /CompatibilityLevel 1.3 /CompressObjects /Off /CompressPages true /ConvertImagesToIndexed true /PassThroughJPEGImages true /CreateJDFFile false /CreateJobTicket false /DefaultRenderingIntent /Perceptual /DetectBlends true /DetectCurves 0.0000 /ColorConversionStrategy /sRGB /DoThumbnails true /EmbedAllFonts true /EmbedOpenType false /ParseICCProfilesInComments true /EmbedJobOptions true /DSCReportingLevel 0 /EmitDSCWarnings false /EndPage -1 /ImageMemory 1048576 /LockDistillerParams true /MaxSubsetPct 100 /Optimize true /OPM 1 /ParseDSCComments true /ParseDSCCommentsForDocInfo true /PreserveCopyPage true /PreserveDICMYKValues true /PreserveEPSInfo true /PreserveFlatness true /PreserveHalftoneInfo false /PreserveOPIComments false /PreserveOverprintSettings true /StartPage 1 /SubsetFonts false /TransferFunctionInfo /Apply /UCRandBGInfo /Preserve /UsePrologue false /ColorSettingsFile () /AlwaysEmbed [ true ] /NeverEmbed [ true ] /AntiAliasColorImages false /CropColorImages true /ColorImageMinResolution 150 /ColorImageMinResolutionPolicy /Warning /DownsampleColorImages true /ColorImageDownsampleType /Bicubic /ColorImageResolution 150 /ColorImageDepth -1 /ColorImageMinDownsampleDepth 1 /ColorImageDownsampleThreshold 1.50000 /EncodeColorImages true /ColorImageFilter /DCTEncode /AutoFilterColorImages true /ColorImageAutoFilterStrategy /JPEG /ColorACSImageDict << /QFactor 0.40 /HSamples [1 1 1 1] /VSamples [1 1 1 1] >> /ColorImageDict << /QFactor 1.30 /HSamples [2 1 1 2] /VSamples [2 1 1 2] >> /JPEG2000ColorACSImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 10 >> /JPEG2000ColorImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 10 >> /AntiAliasGrayImages false /CropGrayImages true /GrayImageMinResolution 150 /GrayImageMinResolutionPolicy /Warning /DownsampleGrayImages true /GrayImageDownsampleType /Bicubic /GrayImageResolution 150 /GrayImageDepth -1 /GrayImageMinDownsampleDepth 2 /GrayImageDownsampleThreshold 1.50000 /EncodeGrayImages true /GrayImageFilter /DCTEncode /AutoFilterGrayImages true /GrayImageAutoFilterStrategy /JPEG /GrayACSImageDict << /QFactor 0.40 /HSamples [1 1 1 1] /VSamples [1 1 1 1] >> /GrayImageDict << /QFactor 1.30 /HSamples [2 1 1 2] /VSamples [2 1 1 2] >> /JPEG2000GrayACSImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 10 >> /JPEG2000GrayImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 10 >> /AntiAliasMonoImages false /CropMonoImages true /MonoImageMinResolution 600 /MonoImageMinResolutionPolicy /Warning /DownsampleMonoImages true /MonoImageDownsampleType /Bicubic /MonoImageResolution 600 /MonoImageDepth -1 /MonoImageDownsampleThreshold 1.50000 /EncodeMonoImages true /MonoImageFilter /CCITTFaxEncode /MonoImageDict << /K -1 >> /AllowPSXObjects false /CheckCompliance [ /None ] /PDFX1aCheck false /PDFX3Check false /PDFXCompliantPDFOnly false /PDFXNoTrimBoxError true /PDFXTrimBoxToMediaBoxOffset [ 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 ] /PDFXSetBleedBoxToMediaBox true /PDFXBleedBoxToTrimBoxOffset [ 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 ] /PDFXOutputIntentProfile (None) /PDFXOutputConditionIdentifier () /PDFXOutputCondition () /PDFXRegistryName () /PDFXTrapped /False /Description << /CHS /CHT /DAN /ESP /FRA /ITA /JPN /KOR /NLD (Gebruik deze instellingen om Adobe PDF-documenten te maken die zijn geoptimaliseerd voor weergave op een beeldscherm, e-mail en internet. De gemaakte PDF-documenten kunnen worden geopend met Acrobat en Adobe Reader 5.0 en hoger.) /NOR /PTB /SUO /SVE /ENU (Use these settings to create Adobe PDF documents best suited for on-screen display, e-mail, and the Internet. Created PDF documents can be opened with Acrobat and Adobe Reader 5.0 and later.) /DEU >> /Namespace [ (Adobe) (Common) (1.0) ] /OtherNamespaces [ << /AsReaderSpreads false /CropImagesToFrames true /ErrorControl /WarnAndContinue /FlattenerIgnoreSpreadOverrides false /IncludeGuidesGrids false /IncludeNonPrinting false /IncludeSlug false /Namespace [ (Adobe) (InDesign) (4.0) ] /OmitPlacedBitmaps false /OmitPlacedEPS false /OmitPlacedPDF false /SimulateOverprint /Legacy >> << /AddBleedMarks false /AddColorBars false /AddCropMarks false /AddPageInfo false /AddRegMarks false /ConvertColors /ConvertToRGB /DestinationProfileName (sRGB IEC61966-2.1) /DestinationProfileSelector /UseName /Downsample16BitImages true /FlattenerPreset << /PresetSelector /MediumResolution >> /FormElements false /GenerateStructure false /IncludeBookmarks false /IncludeHyperlinks false /IncludeInteractive false /IncludeLayers false /IncludeProfiles true /MultimediaHandling /UseObjectSettings /Namespace [ (Adobe) (CreativeSuite) (2.0) ] /PDFXOutputIntentProfileSelector /NA /PreserveEditing false /UntaggedCMYKHandling /UseDocumentProfile /UntaggedRGBHandling /UseDocumentProfile /UseDocumentBleed false >> ] >> setdistillerparams << /HWResolution [2400 2400] /PageSize [595.276 841.890] >> setpagedevice work_6ookup224rajje5yhnu4jdhnee ---- Durham Research Online Deposited in DRO: 06 August 2015 Version of attached �le: Accepted Version Peer-review status of attached �le: Peer-reviewed Citation for published item: Linarelli, John (2017) 'Luck, justice and systemic �nancial risk.', Journal of applied philosophy., 34 (3). pp. 331-352. Further information on publisher's website: https://doi.org/10.1111/japp.12148 Publisher's copyright statement: This is the accepted version of the following article: Linarelli, J. (2017), Luck, Justice and Systemic Financial Risk. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 34(3): 331-352, which has been published in �nal form at https://doi.org/10.1111/japp.12148. This article may be used for non-commercial purposes in accordance With Wiley Terms and Conditions for self-archiving. Additional information: Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-pro�t purposes provided that: • a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • a link is made to the metadata record in DRO • the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Please consult the full DRO policy for further details. Durham University Library, Stockton Road, Durham DH1 3LY, United Kingdom Tel : +44 (0)191 334 3042 | Fax : +44 (0)191 334 2971 https://dro.dur.ac.uk https://www.dur.ac.uk https://doi.org/10.1111/japp.12148 http://dro.dur.ac.uk/15942/ https://dro.dur.ac.uk/policies/usepolicy.pdf https://dro.dur.ac.uk Luck, Justice and Systemic Financial Risk John Linarelli Durham University * Risk in a globalised, interdependent and de-territorialised world has a ubiquitous quality. Consider the complex chains of individual consumer and financial transactions widely attributed with bringing about the 2008-09 economic crisis (the so-called Great Recession), the effects of which remain with us to this day. The Great Recession brought attention to a tragedy of the commons in financial markets, in which market participants, from the first-time home buyer, to the most sophisticated market actors on Wall Street, in the City of London and in other major financial centres, acted in ways beneficial to each of them individually, but when those actions combined together the result was catastrophic. The Great Recession was a man-made disaster with features all too similar to other man-made disasters such as climate change or depletion of natural resources. 1 At least two kinds of risk are at play in complex chains of transactions in financial markets: ordinary market risk and systemic risk. Ordinary market risk is risk that one assumes for oneself when one transacts in a market. For example, if I buy a house, I assume the risk that the value of the house will decline. I also assume the benefit of a rise in the price of the house. Systemic risk is different. My transaction does not impose a risk on me, or at least not only on me, but also on others. The World Economic Forum has identified systemic financial risk as a major global concern in * My sincerest thanks to Orkun Akseli, Carl Cranor, Rita de la Feria, William Lucy, and Pietro Maffettone for their helpful comments. If I have left anyone out of this list, my apologies. My sincerest thanks also to two anonymous referees for their valuable and constructive comments, from which this article has benefitted substantially. All errors are mine. 1 The result is even similar to natural disasters, which in some cases, while not preventable, are foreseeable and precautions to mitigate risk ex ante are reasonable. 2 its 2014 report, Global Risks 2014. 2 That report defines systemic risk as: the risk of ‘breakdowns in an entire system, as opposed to breakdowns in individual parts and components’. Systemic risks are characterized by: – modest tipping points combining indirectly to produce large failures – risk-sharing or contagion, as one loss triggers a chain of others – ’hysteresis,’ or systems being unable to recover equilibrium after a shock. 3 Using this definition, in the actions leading to the Great Recession, market or institutional failure did not only affect the market participants in their own transactions. That would be market risk. Rather, the financial loss spread like a contagion, triggering a chain of catastrophic shocks to the financial markets, leading to a global economic crisis of catastrophic proportions. Such collective harm cases beg for an institutional response. No single action of any one market participant will be sufficient to mitigate systemic risk. Systemic risk mitigation requires substantial coordination, ex ante regulation by authorities, and assurances that regulation will be effective. The law can be designed to either prevent harm from occurring, to provide compensation or other remedy ex post in the event harm occurs, or both. It is in large part a problem relating to the structure of a society, about how institutions shape or limit the range of individual actions. Two moral questions are relevant in these contexts. First, does a person have a 2 World Economic Forum, Global Risks 2014 (9 th ed.). 3 Ibid., p. 12. The Report quotes G.G. Kaufman & K. E Scott, ‘What is Systemic Risk, and Do Bank Regulators Retard or Contribute to It?, Independent Review 7 (2003), pp. 371-391, 371. In an early important article on systemic risk and global financial crises, Steven Schwarcz defined systemic risk in the context of a failure of financial markets as follows: [T]he risk that (i) an economic shock such as market or institutional failure triggers (through a panic or otherwise) either (X) the failure of a chain of markets or institutions or (Y) a chain of significant losses to financial institutions, (ii) resulting in increases in the cost of capital or decreases in its availability, often evidenced by substantial financial-market-price volatility. Steven L. Schwarz, ‘Systemic Risk,’ Georgetown Law Journal 97 (2008), pp. 193-249, 204. See also Viral V. Acharya, Lasse Pederson, Thomas Philippon & Mathew Richardson, ‘Regulating Systemic Risk,’ in Viral V. Acharya & M. Richardson eds., Restoring Financial Stability: How to Repair a Failed System (Hoboken: Wiley): 283-303; Olivier de Bandt & Philip Hartmann, ‘Systemic Risk: A Survey,’ European Central Bank Working Paper 35 (Nov. 2000). 3 moral duty to avoid loss or harm (or risk of loss or harm) to others if her financial transactions contribute in some way, however small, to the loss or harm? In such cases the actions of a person, on her own, cause no harm or loss, but when taken together with the actions of others, causes harm or loss, sometimes substantial harm or loss. I do not mean loss or harm relating to the bargaining power of persons in a contractual privity relationship, such as between debtor and creditor. Rather, I mean loss or harm to third persons not party to any contract with the parties to the transaction. As we shall see, the answer to this question does not proceed along the lines of a simple generalisation around the idea of ‘what if everyone did that’? Second, how should society distribute the risk of loss associated with economic crises? The distribution to which I refer is not distribution within an exchange or transaction, for that would take us back into the debtor-creditor relationship, but risk across persons who may or may not be party to particular exchanges or transactions. The answer to the first question may be relevant to the second but not in all cases or in all approaches to answering these questions. The questions are related to the extent that we want to distribute risks on the basis of some concept of moral responsibility. For the second question, what is relevant is distribution of burdens and benefits through regulation by the state. 4 The primary aim of egalitarian theory is to mitigate or eliminate risk to persons in a way that complies with suitable principles of fair distribution. When we look at the collective nature of these risks, we ask how we might distribute the risk, or at least distribute the burdens of a regulatory regime 4 To be clear, loss or harm cannot be neatly separated from risk of loss or harm. See Claire Finkelstein, ‘Is Risk A Harm,’ University of Pennsylvania Law Review 151 (2003), pp. 963-1001. Risk of loss or harm is simply loss or harm discounted by the probability of the risk-causing event occurring. For example, if a 50% chance of a $100,000 loss exists, then the risk exposure to a rational, risk neutral person is $50,000. In other words, a rational, risk neutral person would buy $50,000 of insurance, if available at an acceptable cost, to cover the potential loss. When we talk about who bears a risk we ask who bears the cost of a risk-causing activity, or in our focus here, on the cost or burdens of taking measures to prevent harm or loss from occurring. 4 designed to avoid or mitigate the risk. A number of ways to distribute the burdens of risk present themselves to us. We could distribute on the basis of a consequentialist account of economic externalities and a requirement that people bear the full social costs for their activities. We could distribute using a contractualist standard of reasonable rejection, such as on the basis of a Rawlsian-type difference principle. As I show below, luck egalitarianism offers promise in working through these issues if we are interested in considerations of both equality and responsibility. These two questions can be understood from interactional and institutional standpoints. For interactional morality, the focus is on individual action. It places demands directly on persons. 5 Another approach is institutional. 6 It takes the morality of communities, or what is usually known as political morality, to be primary. Finance is a human activity, a set of social practices made possible by institutions. These actions, social practices, and institutions have consequences for persons who engage in financial transactions as well for the general population, which includes many who do not engage in financial transactions or engage in transactions with no consequences by themselves. We therefore have to ask what moral obligations institutions ‘deliver’ for us as a community. The second approach takes into account that institutions have great influence on the sorts of risk that might arise in financial markets and how these risks are distributed. Massively complex financial markets, which connect strangers in webs of transactions that can span the globe and cross 5 These concepts are from Thomas Pogge, ‘Cosmopolitanism and Sovereignty,’ Ethics 103(1) (1992), pp. 48-75; Thomas Pogge, John Rawls: His Life and Theory of Justice (Oxford University Press, 2007), pp. 31-34. 6 See Carl F. Cranor, ‘Collective and Individual Duties to Address Global Warming,’ in David M. Driesen, Economic Thought and U.S. Climate Change Policy (MIT Press, 2010), pp. 155-169; Carl F. Cranor, ‘Collective and Individual Duties to Protect the Environment,’ Journal of Applied Philosophy 2 (1985), pp. 243-259. 5 borders with the stroke of a keyboard, cannot exist without institutions. This is a work of moral and political philosophy. My aim here is to articulate the moral concepts that we might want to use either to inform the promulgation of law regulating financial markets or to justify that law from a moral point of view. The moral theories applied below cannot tell us, however, which approaches to financial regulation might be effective in an economic sense, as that is a question of economic policy, not philosophy. An egalitarian asks, of the menu of available economic policies, which is fair or just in a distributional sense? This is not to suggest that egalitarian and other moral concerns have to give way to economic ones or that economics is overriding. In fact a society might accept some levels of cost and inefficiency to obtain a relatively fairer result in law and public policy. We also need to be clear that the discussion proceeds from the assumption that societies are in a position to maintain adequate credit markets and financial institutions for the supply of mortgage credit to homeowners, in economic conditions, including employment conditions and consumption patterns, in which home ownership is economically feasible. This paper does not deal with problems of extreme poverty associated with the lack of functioning credit and other market institutions. Having stated this qualification, the systemic risk flowing from risky financial activities can have serious adverse affects on countries lacking such institutions as well as their populaces. It is also important to clarify that the discussion to follow is directed at the home mortgage market, the collapse of which in specific countries is widely understood to have been a primary contagion for the Great Recession. 6 1. Moral Responsibility of Individual Agents What moral responsibility might an individual agent have in cases in which the agent’s financial decisions are unlikely to cause financial harm or loss to others on their own but when accumulated with the decisions of many others risks substantial financial harm? Preliminarily, I want to rule out the discussion of financial crises for single agents, with no implications of external effects on others, except possibly for persons with which our single agent might have some sort of contractual privity. In such cases, moral responsibility may be relevant, if it is true that failure to pay one’s debts through one’s own fault has moral relevance, though it might not be so easy to distinguish individual circumstances from structural causes for a person’s financial problems. 7 This paper is not about these cases. Rather, the focus here is on financial crises for states and societies, which, given the economic interdependence of states, spill over to be international in effect. The focus in this part of the paper is on interactional morality, on the moral responsibility of persons in these cases. From the standpoint of individual agency, three conditions are relevant, which we can specify as freedom-relevant, practical and epistemic. 8 The freedom-relevant condition captures the idea that a person can be morally responsible only if she acts freely. It deals with the question of alternate possibilities. The basic intuition is that we cannot be morally responsible unless we could do otherwise. This may be false, if compatibilists are right. A ‘metaphysics free’ version of free agency can be posed here, focusing on the intrusion of institutions and social structure on agency. Intervention by these socially constructed forces might take away from the 7 See Iris Marion Young, Responsibility for Justice (Oxford University Press, 2011). As explained in the section to follow, a focus on desert rather than on choice can help to deal with when so-called bad brute luck should be neutralized in debt contracts. 8 I adapt the ‘freedom-relevant’ language and concept from John Martin Fischer and Mark Ravizza eds., Perspectives on Moral Responsibility (Cornell University Press, 1993), p. 8. For a full account on the epistemic condition, see George Sher, Who Knew: Responsibility Without Awareness (Oxford University Press, 2009). 7 voluntariness of an act and might prevent an agent from being attributively responsible and hence affect the blameworthiness of an act. 9 Or, they might alter the determination of which principles it is reasonable to reject and therefore affect substantive responsibility, or what an agent owes as moral duties to others. 10 These considerations have special relevance in the case of contributory harm of the sort we are talking about here, where chains of events might combine to result in harm to many people. It just might be true, as an empirical matter, that institutions, if sufficiently pervasive, restrict freedom in such a way as to relieve a person of moral responsibility. 11 The practical condition deals with the question whether a person’s actions make a difference. Why do we care about the agent’s actions or failure to act? The practical condition is strictly necessary for a consequentialist argument to be successful. Consequentialism condemns an act only if it makes a difference. In the case of mass financial harm of the sort under consideration here, an agent’s act on its own likely does make a difference, but the difference may be negligible, or, in Derek Parfit’s terminology, imperceptible. Parfit argues that it is a mistake to claim that if some act produces imperceptible effects, then it cannot be wrong, because the sum of imperceptible effects adds up to perceptible effects. The contribution of a single person matters. 12 But the sort of generalisation arguments that consequentalists employ in these kinds of mass harm cases cannot lead to the conclusion that no one 9 I use here Scanlon’s distinction between attributive and substantive responsibility. T.M. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Harvard University Press, 1998), pp. 248-294. 10 These concepts are from Scanlon, n. 9. 11 A contractualist might base the freedom-relevant condition on Scanlon’s Causal Thesis. Ibid., pp. 261-276. 12 Derek Parfit, Reasons and Persons (Oxford University Press, 1984). Parfit’s more recent work is Kantian in approach. Derek Parfit, On What Matters (Oxford University Press, 2011), Vol. 1, pp. 301- 320. See also Shelly Kagan, ‘Do I Make a Difference?,’ Philosophy and Public Affairs 39(2) (2011), pp. 105-141. 8 should take action that could result in harm collectively when many do it. 13 There may be some threshold at which some people doing the particular act might too low a number to trigger the feared harm, or it may actually be desirable if those persons so act. A potential weakness for consequentialism to operate in these complex financial cases is the need for substantial information available to persons to know which of them can act. It is less demanding on persons if institutions do the allocating of permissible actions for them. For contractualists (and other deontologists), bad consequences are not dispositive to the outcome of moral deliberation or appraisal, but are still relevant. The main concern in a contractualist account is not whether some moral principle prohibits acts that contribute imperceptible differences to bad consequences but that it might place unreasonably disproportionate burdens on a person to avoid contributing to harm to others. The focus of contractualist argument is not on consequences alone or primarily but on why it is wrong to act or not to act in the face of consequences. The epistemic condition relates to the knowledge of the agent deliberating on action. What if an agent neither knows nor should have known that their act causes or contributes to harm? There are a number of elements in a full account of the epistemic condition. For example, George Sher’s ‘full epistemic condition’ or FEC for moral responsibility specifies a number of conditions for praise or blameworthiness. 14 Two 13 Questions about generalisation became prominent in the work of Marcus Singer, with the publication in 1961 of his Generalization in Ethics - An Essay in the Logic of Ethics, with the Rudiments of a System of Moral Philosophy (Knopf, 1961). The above is influenced by Edna Ullman-Margalit’s critique of Singer. Edna Ullman Margalit, ‘The Generalization Argument: Where Does the Obligation Lie?,’ The Journal of Philosophy 73 (15) (1976), pp. 511-522, p. 513. 14 Sher’s FEC is as follows: When someone performs an act in a way that satisfies the voluntariness condition, and when he also satisfies any other conditions for responsibility that are independent of the epistemic condition, he is responsible for his act's morally or prudentially relevant feature if, but only if, he either (1) is consciously aware that the act has that feature (i.e., is wrong or foolish or right or prudent) when he performs it; or else 9 of these conditions very roughly comprise what in the law might be understood as a negligence standard: knew or should have known. If a person knows or should know that their actions harm others, then the epistemic condition is satisfied for declaring their actions to be wrong. Sher also argues for moral wrongness when some act ‘falls below some applicable standard,’ and ‘is caused by the interaction of some combination of his constitutive attitudes, dispositions, and traits’. 15 This latter standard captures the idea of greed in a financial context: a greedy person has the wrong constitutive attitudes and is morally responsible for the financial harm she causes or contributes to, even if she does not know, nor ought to have known, of the harm. This distinction is important, for example, to distinguish home lenders who enter into a subprime mortgage to be able to afford a decent home for their family and those who do so because they have been irresponsible about credit. Using the three conditions, we can test out alternative moral principles using well- accepted constructivist methods. Start with a simple contributory harm principle: Principle CH: It is wrong to act in ways that contribute to harm to another person. What does it mean to contribute to harm to others? The contribution feature in Principle CH assists in compliance with the practical condition. Implicit in Principle CH is that an imperceptible difference has moral significance, but we know that an imperceptible difference on its own is not a significant problem for either consequentialist or contractualists. The main concern about Principle CH, at least to a (2) is unaware that the act is wrong or foolish despite having evidence for its wrongness or foolishness his failure to recognize which (a) falls below some applicable standard, and (b) is caused by the interaction of some combination of his constitutive attitudes, dispositions, and traits; or else (3) is unaware that the act is right or prudent despite having made enough cognitive contact with the evidence for its rightness or prudence to enable him to perform the act on that basis. Sher, n. 8, p. 143. Sher calls FEC ‘complicated and unlovely’ Ibid., p. 144. 15 Ibid., p. 143. 10 contractualist, is not whether it prohibits acts contributing an imperceptible difference to bad consequences but that it might place unreasonably disproportionate burdens on a person to avoid contributing to harm to others. 16 This is, in contrast, not a problem for consequentialists. The disproportionate burdens problem relates not to the practical condition but to the freedom-relevant condition. Principle CH lacks constraints of reasonableness, core to contractualism. Principle CH is too demanding to be contractualist though it may work as a consequentialist principle. Finally, Principle CH does not address the epistemic condition. Consider the following modification: Principle CH1: It is wrong to act in ways that contribute to harm to another person (or n persons) if an agent’s refraining from acting would not place disproportionate burdens on the agent. Notions of reasonableness and separateness of persons come into Principle CH2. They are essential requirements in contractualism and serve to implement the freedom- relevant condition. These concepts give us some latitude to lessen the demands of generalisation arguments. The problem with these principles so far, however, is they do not address the epistemic condition. What if an agent does not know nor could have known of the effects of her actions when combined with the actions of numerous others? Agents are unlikely to be morally responsible for outcomes about which they could not have reasonably known. Our reactive attitude in such cases will not be to condemn such acts. Moreover, there might be cases in which a person does not know or could not have known of the risks associated with their actions, yet we still might hold them morally responsible if we can point to some failure to meet an accepted standard of behaviour of the person 16 Moreover, the focus of Principle CH is on wrongness and not undesirability as there may be many things which are undesirable but which do not involve morality. It may be undesirable to eat with one’s hands rather than with cutlery or chopsticks but it is not a moral problem if many people engage in sloppy eating. 11 which would merit moral responsibility. 17 An agent likely has reason to reject attempts to make her morally responsible for actions she had no way of knowing would result in the harm they cause or which are not the result of failures to comply with well-accepted standards of behaviour relating to financial risk. The epistemic condition suggests a further modification of our principle: Principle CH2: It is wrong to act in ways that contribute to harm to another person (or n persons) if (1a) the agent knew or should have known that her actions would contribute to the harm or (1b) the agent’s actions fail to meet some applicable standard of behaviour resulting from a combination of constitutive attitudes, dispositions, and traits; and (2) the agent’s refraining from acting would not place disproportionate burdens on her own freedom of action. Principle CH2 meets all three of our conditions. The harm contribution principle embedded within it meets the practical condition. The epistemic principles embedded in 1a and 1b meet the epistemic condition. The disproportionate burdens requirement in 2 brings Principle CH2 into compliance with the freedom-relevant condition. The ‘some applicable standard’ language in 1b is from Sher’s notion of ‘some standard of rationality or reasonableness’, which he argues are canonically expressed in tort and criminal law. 18 With Principle CH2 in hand, we can now begin to get more specific about financial harm contexts. In such contexts, not all of the participants in the collective action that is causing the harm are doing the same thing. Actors in a financial crisis situation are differentiated, in a way that makes a difference to moral responsibility. 17 I am not convinced the applicable standard element, found in 1b of Principle CH2, is needed if we have a properly objective and expansive ‘should have known’ element, but I will take Sher’s approach as stipulated for our purposes. As we will see below, it helps us to clothe the ‘greedy homeowner’ with moral responsibility despite their lack of awareness of the harm their risky action produces. 18 Sher, n. 8, p. 80. 12 Some of the relevant agents are unsophisticated consumers. Others are sophisticated financial institutions. The actions of some make a very significant difference to the crisis. Others are simply first time homebuyers working hard to buy a decent house for their family. Many individual actions by themselves may have been legally permissible and in fact encouraged by government policy, such as by mortgage securitisation, which the US federal government subsidised for many years, partly to encourage individual home ownership by those least able to afford it, though also to support the market for securities produced from mortgage securitisation, so-called mortgage-backed securities. 19 To put some details in the analysis, assume a five-person society comprised of ‘citizen’, ‘lender’, ‘consumer borrower’, and ‘market professional’. We can further divide ‘market professional’ into sophisticates and non-sophisticates. The lender lends mortgage loans to the consumer borrower. An example of a market professional who is also a sophisticate is a financial institution such as a bank, a loan originator or an institution responsible for securitising mortgages, such as a ‘packager’ of loans. 20 An example of a market professional who is probably not a sophisticate is a residential real estate agent. The financial institution could produce and trade in financial products that come from the debt contracts between borrower and lender. An example of such a product is mortgage-backed securities. The citizen is a representative third party who suffers harm from the financial activities of the others. The citizen has no moral responsibility but will suffer great harm and will not be discussed further in this part of the paper. What is the moral responsibility of these archetypes in our idealised society? 19 See Afit Mian & Amir Sufi, House of Debt (University of Chicago Press, 2014), pp. 95-105. 20 Use of ‘person’, ‘agent,’ or ‘actor,’ in this paper refers to natural or legal persons as the context warrants. 13 Much of what I am about to say is tentative because it depends on empirical considerations and is therefore outside of the scope of moral philosophy. But we can draw basic conclusions. Start with the single consumer borrower. An example might be a first time homebuyer who took out a subprime mortgage. The adverse effects of the subprime mortgage market on financial markets in the most recent financial crisis are well understood. It may be privately beneficial for the homebuyer to enter a mortgage that pushes to the limits of affordability, such as a risky subprime mortgage. It may also be necessary. The borrower may need to buy the house to get her children into a decent school because her government fails to provide equality of opportunity in education. She may need to get on the home buying ladder to leave an oppressive rental market or because her government fails to provide decent social housing. Or, she may simply want to buy better accommodation. Other alternatives are that she has poor credit because of bad choices, or is living beyond her means. Regardless of the reasons why a borrower enters into a risky mortgage, when many people enter into similarly risky mortgages, the result can be disastrous. Let’s apply Principle CH2 to our consumer borrower. Two problems seem apparent, and they stem from the epistemic condition. First, if we understand Principle CH2 to reflect consequentialist insights, how does an agent know if they are in the category of agents who should not take the action resulting in the imperceptible difference? Certainly there will be some level of risky mortgages that will be acceptable or even beneficial. There may be some optimal number of risky mortgages posing low risks to the financial system yet benefit poor recipients greatly. Second, how shall our individual agent weigh or compare good and bad consequences? If she is required to aggregate for bad consequences for the financial system, should she not 14 also be required to aggregate for good consequences? It is likely that the consumer borrower cannot meet the knew or should have known standard in Principle CH2. There may however be a ‘greedy homeowner’ category if particular constitutive attitudes make a consumer borrower profligate or risk friendly. If our consumer borrower does not fall into this category a further impediment to holding her morally responsible, which comes from Principle CH2’s contractualist features, is that refraining from entering into a mortgage transaction may place disproportionate burdens on the consumer borrower’s freedom of action if she is a first time home buyer trying to enter the property ladder, a parent trying to make a decent life for her family in an unjust society with inadequate social housing, and so on. The bottom line is that there will be many contexts in which the consumer borrower is not morally responsible for mass financial harm. The lender situation is different. Here we likely have a situation in which Principle CH2 imposes moral responsibility. The actions of lenders in many cases are likely to make a significant difference. They have likely significantly contributed to harm. Some of the more sophisticated market participants knew or should have known that their risky activities would be the cause of significant financial harm. If they were greedy or in pursuit of extraordinary profits, their particular constitutive attitudes provide the necessary element to comply with the epistemic condition in Principle CH2, regardless of whether they knew or should have known of the risks.. It is doubtful that lenders suffer disproportionate burdens if they refrain from actions that lead to systemic financial harm. With the existence of established capital markets in the form of stock exchanges, the lender’s shareholders have the option to move their financial holdings to other investments to produce similar returns but which would not contribute to systemic financial risk. Moral responsibility seems clear in 15 many lender cases. Consider the sophisticated market professional. Here is a stylised example. ‘Financial institution’ securitizes home mortgages. They use structured finance to pool loans and create securities from loan pools, rated and classified by default risk. They know that some of the mortgages they acquire were created as a result of subprime lending and that this subprime lending dramatically increases the risk of default by borrowers on loans. They know that securitization facilitates subprime lending and the benefits from it. They also know that they are not the only enterprise in the securitization business and that there is a cascading risk from creating securities from subprime loans that goes beyond the risk of default by borrowers. 21 Principle CH2 seems to clearly place moral responsibility on this sophisticated market professional to refrain from contributing to systemic financial risk. This financial institution contributes to systemic risk and the harm that follows and knows or should know that it is doing so. They and their shareholders plausibly have alternative investment strategies and so could reasonably refrain from contributing to this risk. That they may make less of a return on investment in these alternative investment strategies may be true, but their focus only on maximising their own gain regardless of the consequences is unreasonable and suggests a set of constitutive attitudes that would violate Principle CH2. What about unsophisticated market professional? Consider the following example. ‘Real estate agent’ works hard to assist first time homebuyers in buying houses. She is the sole wage earner for her family. She does not work on the financing side of the industry. She is aware that some of her clients enter into subprime 21 I use the subprime mortgage example only to provide concreteness to the case study. The availability of subprime mortgages has been severely restricted since the Great Recession. 16 mortgages, but she is not involved in setting up these mortgages. She could try to refer her clients to more conservative mortgage brokers but her firm requires her to use a particular broker and if she violated this policy, she could lose her job. Even if she could refer her clients to other mortgage brokers, there is the possibility that this will reduce her own income substantially, and she feels that she should be able to rely on the buyer’s own choices in the matter. Real estate agent is aware that the above financial institution is securitizing many of these risky loans and the risky loans of others. She thinks that one day the bubble will indeed burst. It is unclear whether Principle CH2 imposes moral responsibility on the real estate agent. The conduct of the Real Estate Agent likely only meets the epistemic conditions of Principle CH2. She knows there is a problem and her discontinuing her actions might be the right result if we focus solely on a consequentialist account of imperceptible difference, but under our Principle CH2 requiring that she act might violate the freedom relevant condition – it may place disproportionate burdens on her freedom of action. It would benefit society if she stopped working in her line of business but it may be difficult for us (society) to ask her to do so as a matter of individual choice, unless we give her other options. Here we see that institutions may be needed to solve this collective action problem. To conclude, this first part of the paper is moral philosophy about the actions of individual agents when faced with financial decision making. Does a person have a moral duty to avoid a particular financial transaction or set of financial transactions that might contribute in some way, however slight, to harm to others who may not be parties to the transaction or set of transactions? The answer is, it depends. To get this question to be tractable, I developed a five-person idealised society comprised of citizen, consumer borrower, lender, and two different kinds of market professionals, 17 depending on the level of their sophistication about finance. I then evaluated the conduct of these agents using a moral principle that I worked out of the conditions in which persons might be morally responsible for their individual actions in mass or collective financial harm cases. Consumer borrowers are unlikely to have moral duties to avoid financial transactions unless they have some special knowledge of the effects of their acts on others or if they fail to meet some applicable standard of conduct, such as when they are risk friendly profligate spenders. The lender is morally responsible in most cases and will owe duties to avoid financial systemic risk in their lending activities. The market professional cases are unclear and depend primarily on the level of knowledge of the market professional and their ability to do otherwise without disproportionate burdens on their livelihood. The citizen is an innocent bystander and has no moral duties in the contexts of individual or interactional morality. But our idealized citizen may have a role in promoting institutions to deal with the problems of collective financial harm. The analysis so far does not deal with the role of institutions. On the role of institutions, Ullman Margalit has argued that the generalisation argument is a derivative obligation imposed on individuals, with the primary obligation on the relevant community to impose these obligations on individual agents. 22 According to Ullman-Margalit, the relevant community has the primary obligation to ‘see to it’ that an appropriate number of community members do not do the putatively risky or harmful action in question. Obligations on agents will flow not from interactional morality, or at least not only from interactional morality, but from the authority of the community to command agents to act or refrain from acting in particular ways. 22 Ullman-Margalit, n. 13, pp. 517-520. 18 2. The Distribution of Systemic Financial Risk Societies can and do allocate financial risk in a number of ways, either by accident, design, or a combination of both. Actual policy prescriptions in banking and finance areas rely primary on concerns about macroeconomics and stability in national economies and the global economy. 23 Distributional considerations rarely enter the mix and when they do, they do so haphazardly. My aim here is to fill that gap by offering a way to morally justify the distribution of systemic financial risk. As explained below, I develop an approach relying on resource-based luck egalitarianism to allocate systemic financial risk. In addition to morally justifiable legal principles at work in the distribution of systemic financial risk, we also want the rules to be rational and efficacious. In a wide reflective equilibrium, we should inquire about non-moral considerations, such as the economic effects of legal rules. Economics is influential in real-world institutional design and it provides tools for understanding how public policy designed around principles of political morality might actually operate in a society. In economic terms, systemic financial risk is an externality. It contributes to other externalities in the housing market, such as foreclosure or repossession externalities. 24 Financial crises create a classic market failure problem. If firms and individuals act in their own interest when they make decisions involving financial risk, they take only their own costs and benefits into account. More accurately, they take into account only costs they personally bear and benefits they directly receive. Iwan Anabtawi and 23 With the possible exception of the UK government, governments rarely if ever rely even on cost- benefit analysis to assess the effects of financial regulation. John C. Coates IV, ‘Cost Benefit Analysis of Financial Regulation: Case Studies and Implications’, Yale Law Journal 124 (2015), pp. 882-1345. 24 ‘Foreclosure’ is US terminology whilst ‘repossession is UK terminology. I rely on UK terminology in this paper. 19 Steven Schwarcz describes this as asymmetry in the distribution of gains and losses associated with financial decisions. 25 Financial decisions have undesirable spill-over effects, or what economists call negative externalities. Firms and individuals often do not bear the full social costs for their financial activities. A classic example of these externalities was the effect of subprime lending in the United States and elsewhere on the global economy, leading to the Great Recession. 26 Though some disagreement amongst economists persists about the causes of the Great Recession, some consensus has emerged. The financial crisis leading to the Great Recession was in substantial part triggered by a significant weakening of underwriting standards by lenders. This process began in late 2004 and continued on into early 2007. With the demand for ever-increasing returns from investors, participants in global financial markets (originators, underwriters, asset managers, credit rating agencies and investors) became complacent about risk. When real estate prices began to fall in the United States, defaults on subprime mortgages, many with adjustable rates triggering to higher rates, became substantial. These events led to a substantial decline in consumption by households. When credit rating agencies began to downgrade securitisation products, the market began to unravel. The result was spill-overs with dramatic consequences resulting in the worst economic crises in recorded history. The spread of loss was like a contagion, spreading from a few real estate markets in California and Florida across the globe. The single participants in these global webs of transactions each privately benefited in particular transactions but the combination of their actions lead to a collapse of the global economy. To bring egalitarianism to the discussion, let’s postulate two simple and highly 25 Iwan Anabrtawi & Steven Scharwz, ‘Regulating Systemic Risk: Towards an Analytical Framework, Notre Dame Law Review 86 (2011), pp. 1349-1412. 26 What follows is from The President’s Working Group on Financial Markets, Policy Statement on Financial Market Developments (March 2008). 20 stylized cases, one called ‘easy credit,’ reflecting what might be conditions before a financial crisis, and ‘tight credit’, reflecting what might be conditions after a financial crisis, when government increases regulation, ostensibly to decrease systemic risk. These states of affairs are simply placeholders for any government policy with the effect of making home mortgages more or less affordable to borrowers. As in the prior section, assume a five-person society comprised of ‘lender’, ‘borrower’, ‘market professional’ and ‘citizen’. The focus will be on lender, borrower and citizen, as the effects on them will be most important and effects on market professionals will be overlapping with and deriving from the effects on these primary actors. In addition the distributional implications favouring the lender over the borrower can be significant. 27 I will go step-by-step through the problem from the standpoint of a prominent version of luck egalitarianism, known as resource-based luck egalitarianism, the main proponents of which are Ronald Dworkin and Eric Rakowski, though Dworkin did not consider himself a luck egalitarian. 28 I will use Dworkin’s concept of an auction for the division of resources at the initial stages of society, his concept of hypothetical insurance to deal with inequalities, and his distinction between brute and option luck. A resource-based approach to luck egalitarianism allows us to avoid the propensity of welfare egalitarianism to compensate those who deliberately cultivate expensive tastes and even those not responsible for their expensive tastes and have so-called bad price luck. 29 In a resource-based account, we can avoid catering to people with 27 Mian & Sufi, n. 19, pp. 19-20. 28 Ronald Dworkin, ‘Equality of Resources’ in Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality (Harvard University Press, 2000), pp. 65-119; Ronald Dworkin, ‘Equality, Luck & Hierarchy’, Philosophy and Public Affairs 31(2003), pp. 190-198; Eric Rakowski, Equal Justice (Oxford University Press, 1991). Of course, there are many who offer a resource-based account of egalitarianism. The emphasis here is on responsibility-sensitive accounts characterized as luck egalitarian. 29 As set forth in Dworkin, n. 28; G.A. Cohen, ‘Expensive Tastes Rides Again’, in Justine Burley ed., 21 expensive tastes in homes, or more generally, to people who seek substantial increases in their well-being from risky uses of credit. Government intervention is an admittedly crude instrument for managing people’s tastes and preferences and we may not care so much about catering to people’s expensive tastes, even if those tastes are not subject to the control of the people who have them. We are, rather, concerned about more serious effects of systemic financial risk on basic levels of need for housing and credit. 30 Private home ownership is a resource. As Dworkin argues in the first paragraph of ‘Equality of Resources’, the paper said to have begun modern-day accounts of luck egalitarianism, ‘equality of resources is a matter of equality in whatever resources are owned privately by individuals’. 31 Dworkin goes on to explain that private ownership ‘is not a single, unique relationship between a person and a material resource, but an open-textured relationship many aspects of which must be fixed politically’.’ 32 So, Dworkin concludes, ‘the question of what division of resources is an equal division must to some degree include the question of what powers someone who is assigned a resource thereby gains, and that in turn must include the further question of his right to veto whatever changes in those powers might be threatened through politics’. 33 Rakowski argues similarly, assuming that the resources available for division would be held privately and limiting his argument to those resources ‘that are placed in Dworkin and His Critics (Blackwell, 2004), pp. 3-29; Richard Arneson, ‘Equality and Equal Opportunity for Welfare,’ Philosophical Studies 56 (1989), pp. 77-93; John Roemer, Theories of Distributive Justice (Harvard University Press, 1996). 30 A welfare-based proponent might respond by arguing for an objective rather than subjective measure of welfare, through the development of some sort of objective list of acceptable levels of credit or home ownership. Whilst an objective welfare account might well be amenable to development, it adds unnecessary complexity when it comes to developing actual heuristics to guide public policy, and risks of dissolving into a resource based account at the level of public policy. 31 Dworkin, n. 28, p. 65. 32 Ibid. 33 Ibid. 22 individuals’ hands.’ 34 As we will discover below, when we enquire into the economic incidents of private home ownership financed by mortgage credit, we can disaggregate private ownership into a number of other resources. Let’s take a look at the private ownership rights of our archetypal agents in our simplified four-person model. We need to identify what could plausibly be identified as resources to be distributed to and from the various agents. From this position of identification of resources, we can then decide how to distribute these resources using a luck egalitarian framework. We will also need to understand the risks associated with these resource allocations and how to distribute these risks in a luck egalitarian framework, if these risks have the potential to change significant features or the values of these resources. The typical mortgage contract allocates rights and responsibilities to lender and borrower. In the usual arrangement found in countries maintaining substantial owner- occupied residential patterns financed by credit, 35 the borrower is a homeowner, residing in the home. The borrower is the debtor in a relationship of secured credit with a financial institution serving as the creditor. The resources the borrower receives are home ownership and credit. If the mortgage has a fixed interest rate, the borrower enjoys the benefits of that fixed rate and the resulting certainty of fixed payments over the life of the mortgage. If the mortgage interest rate is adjustable, the borrower benefits from downward interest rate adjustments but bears the risk of upward adjustments. A significant expected benefit of real property ownership is that the borrower gets to keep, or effectively ‘owns’, the market appreciation in the value of the property, though they also bear the full risk of market declines in property values. 34 Rakowski, n. 28, p. 66. 35 See Dan Andrews & Aida Caldera Sanchez, Drivers of Homeownership Rates in Selected OECD Countries (OECD, 2011); Jon Palmer, ‘Brits buy homes, the Germans rent – which of us has got it right?’, The Guardian, 19 March 2011. 23 The lender’s resources include those of the typical secured creditor, including return on investment in home loans in the form of interest on funds lent. For adjustable rate mortgages, the lender benefits from interest rate increases but these have to be offset by increased costs of funds from depositors caused by general interest rate increases in the economy. Our model has simplified matters but we could add the resource that a typical lender does not lend its own funds but the funds of its depositors if it is a deposit institution such as a commercial bank. A lending resource that a bank has is leverage. Leverage ratios are a longstanding area of bank regulation. Finally, a lender is a creditor with a fixed claim on the asset securing the debt, which means that it can repossess the house serving as the security for the mortgage in the event of the borrower’s default on the mortgage. The citizen, a simplification for a typical person outside of the borrower-lender relationship, has the potential to enjoy economic stability as a result of the mitigation of systemic financial risk. Economic stability may be seen as a public good in an economic sense. 36 The citizen also benefits from the spread of private home ownership, to the extent that it benefits the community, as the social science evidence indicated. 37 Turning to the risks associated with the resources to be allocated, the lender has a fixed claim on the borrower and her asset during the duration of the mortgage, though some sharing of risk occurs on adjustable rate mortgages. It is fair to say that the 36 On the public good of financial stability, see Charles Wyplosz, ‘International Financial Stability’, in Inge Kaul, Isabelle Grunberg & Marc A. Stern eds., Global Public Goods: International Cooperation in the 21 st Century (United Nations Development Programme, 1999), pp. 152-189; Mads Andenas & Iris H. Y. Chiu, ‘Financial Stability and Legal Integration in Financial Regulation, European Law Review 38 (2013), pp. 335-359. The distinction between financial and economic stability is discussed below. 37 The literature is substantial. See, e.g., Edward Glaeser & Denise DiPasquale, ‘Incentives & Social Capital: Are Homeowners Better Citizens?’, Journal of Urban Economics 45 (1999), pp. 354-384; Sidney Verba, Kay Lehman Schlozman, & Henry Brady, Voice and Equality: Civic Volunteerism in American Politics (Harvard University Press, 1995). 24 lender has a fairly fixed income stream regardless of the value of the asset or the state of the economy. A mortgage is a debt contract, and these tend to be inflexible. The borrower benefits from market appreciation of the value of the house but also bears the risk of the decline in its value. The borrower bears the risk of default, which includes repossession and ultimate loss of home, for any number of reasons, either from her own actions or from a general downturn in the economy in which the borrower is put under the stress of reduced income or loss of employment. The lender does bear some systemic risk associated with serial repossessions, as they are in the business of lending and not home sales and generally disfavour having to deal with large inventories of repossessed houses in distressed markets. The citizen suffers from the effects of systemic risk and repossession externalities, and this is so regardless of her position in the housing market. The effects of systemic risk and repossession externalities on the citizen are both specific and general. The effects on the citizen are specific in a territorial or local sense. A citizen in a local context (such as in a housing estate) in which there have been substantial numbers of repossessions will likely suffer substantial loss as their net worth and means to promote their lives and to support their families decreases. If their net worth is low or negative to begin with, the harm can be catastrophic. The effects on the citizen are general in that national and even global economic declines contribute significant harm to the citizen, particularly if the citizen is of limited economic means. Now that we have identified the relevant resources and the risks associated with those resources, the next step is to decide how to distribute them in responsibility- sensitive ways. Assume that the initial stages of Dworkin’s island auction have occurred. Once the auction meeting Dworkin’s envy test has concluded, inequalities will still have to be dealt with as society progresses through subsequent market 25 exchanges and relationships. Dworkin developed the notion of hypothetical insurance to determine which inequalities would be justifiable. 38 The hypothetical insurance procedure is designed to be ambition sensitive but not endowment sensitive, which means that differences in people’s ambitions might result in unobjectionable inequalities but that inequalities from endowments such as disabilities, native talents, or accidents of birth should be neutralised. The hypothetical insurance model can be adapted for the situation here. For Dworkin, insurance ‘provides a link between brute and option luck, because the decision to buy or reject catastrophe insurance is a calculated gamble.’ 39 We do the same thing here, analogizing home mortgage defaults of the serial nature at issue here to be a catastrophe, albeit of an economic kind. The question becomes: how to neutralise bad brute luck in mortgage transactions and systemically? In a hypothetical decision making process about whether to buy insurance, which kinds of bad brute luck would it be rational for the borrower and the citizen to reject? The notion of insurance is a tempering device to get persons behind a veil of ignorance to assess what their insurance needs might rationally be in the mortgage market. We want to assess what a rational person would be willing to pay in insurance premiums ex ante to avoid risk in that market. In this process, we also will assess what a hypothetical insurer would be willing to underwrite. Of course, we need to take into account that our insurer is hypothetical and that in actual practice there may be no insurer willing to underwrite the risks we deal with here. Dworkin’s distinction between brute luck and option luck tells us a great deal about the distribution of systemic financial risk. The distinction between ordinary 38 The terminology of emerging inequalities is from Alexander Brown, Ronald Dworkin’s Theory of Equality: Domestic and Global Perspectives (Palgrave Macmillan 2009), pp. 58-63. 39 Ibid, p. 59. 26 market risk and systemic risk aligns closely with Dworkin’s distinction between option luck and brute luck. According to Dworkin, ordinary market risk is not morally arbitrary, in the sense that people who make market decisions, ‘take a gamble’ and are subject to option luck. 40 In this account, making a market decision is a choice. The harm associated with systemic financial risk, in contrast, seems a clear case of bad brute luck. Systemic financial risk has the potential to harm someone even if they had nothing to do with the transactions causing the harm. Exposure to systemic financial risk is an unfortunate circumstance having nothing to do with choosing but with being a participant in a market economy. In the context of the global financial crisis, a person like our citizen was out of the market entirely, without any mortgage, not involved in financial markets in any way, and yet losses cascading systemically through the financial system and the economy as a result of the actions of others caused her substantial loss of resources. But the distinction between brute and option luck, reflecting a distinction between choice and circumstances, might not be easy to make in many cases. 41 The elusiveness of the distinction can be handled in two ways. First, as explained below hypothetical insurance rules out insuring against expensive tastes. Second and alternatively, Richard Arneson offers a solution to this problem by asking us to distinguish between choice and desert catering luck egalitarianism. 42 Choice is essential but background facts also need to be considered. Here, we may give some latitude to borrowers with particular characteristics. Principle CH2 reflects the notion of desert. Assume two borrowers enter into identical risky mortgages they can barely 40 Dworkin explains that ‘option luck is a matter of how deliberate and calculated gambles turn out – whether someone gains or loses through accepting an isolated risk her or she should have anticipated and might have declined’. Dworkin, n. 28, p. 73. 41 Dworkin so acknowledges. Ronald Dworkin, ‘Justice, Insurance, and Luck’, in Dworkin, n. 28, pp. 320-350, 324. 42 Richard J. Arneson, ‘Luck Egalitarianism Interpreted and Defended’, Philosophical Topics 32 (2004), pp. 1-20. 27 afford. We might want to neutralise the bad luck of a borrower who is a first time home buyer, has been prudent with her finances, is in need of a decent home for her family with good schools, is in no position to know of the imperceptible effects of her risky mortgage on others, and may have a limited understanding of the effects of a risky mortgage on herself. 43 On the other hand, a profligate big spender with expensive tastes who pushes herself to the limits of affordability so that she can have a house she can conspicuously show off to her friends and colleagues will be less deserving of relief. We can, however, keep our account parsimonious and rely on the hypothetical insurance procedure to deal with this particular problem. With the above established we are now in a position to assess the risks our agents want to insure and whether a prudent insurer in our hypothetical world would provide the insurance at a premium our agents would be prepared to accept. 44 Let’s start with the borrower. Assume the borrower does not know her personal traits, whether she is the profligate big spender or first time home buyer, whether her actions will contribute to systemic financial risk, whether she will be adversely affected by systemic financial risk, whether she is rich or poor, or whether she has expensive tastes and bad price luck. In these hypothetical conditions, the borrower would want to insure against risk of loss of adequate housing resulting from adverse economic conditions or the terms and conditions of the mortgage contract. Adequacy of housing can be assessed relative to the society in which the borrower lives. 45 The borrower would want to insure against catastrophic loss of housing as a result of significant economic crises. The Borrower would not, however, insure to have significant 43 See Brown, n. 38, p. 59 on investment luck. 44 For a somewhat similar discussion about dangerous activities, natural disasters, business losses and business profits, See Rakowski, n. 28, pp. 79-87. 45 It is common in egalitarian theory to measure rights and opportunities in terms relative to the society in question. See, e.g, Norman Daniels, Just Health Care (Cambridge University Press, 1985), p. 53, in which Daniels argues that health care is a social good that is necessary for societies to provide to maintain normal species functioning at an opportunity range determined by one’s society. 28 housing wealth relative to other society members, or against extravagant tastes in housing. Very few people in a society acquire significant housing wealth or have extravagant tastes, and so the probability of a person being in these categories outside of the veil of ignorance is low. Alternatively stated, the risk of being not wealthy is very high and so the premiums to insure against it would be prohibitive. 46 Short of outright loss of home, the borrower would likely find it problematic to bear all or a significant proportion of the risk of loss from severe declines in home values. It is plausible to believe that she would want insurance coverage similar to natural disaster insurance. If a borrower were to lose a home or if the home were significantly damaged as a result of fire or a tornado, the borrower would likely have insurance to cover such losses. 47 In fact natural disaster insurance is usually required as a condition in a mortgage contract. Finally, the borrower behind a veil of ignorance might also find it problematic if others, such as the lender or its constituencies, such as the lender’s shareholders and depositors, 48 were to benefit from her bad brute luck. 49 Our borrower would probably not want the lender to benefit from the borrower’s default on a mortgage, resulting in borrower’s loss of her home. In addition, such a structure of the debt contract would produce poor incentives for the lender and hold the borrower hostage to the acts of predatory lenders. The borrower would want the lender to share in the downsides the borrower faces in the housing market. In short, no good brute luck from bad brute luck. As for the lender, there is substantial evidence that financial institutions have for 46 See Rakowski, n. 28, pp. 122. 47 Miaf & Sufi, n. 19, pp. 17-18. 48 As the U.S. Supreme Court has stated: ‘The relationship of bank and depositor is that of debtor and creditor, founded on contract.’ Bank ov Marin v. England, 385 U.S. 99 (1966). 49 Carl Knight, ‘Benefiting from Injustice and Brute Luck’, Social Theory and Practice 39 (2010), pp. 581-598. 29 many years pre- and post-Great Recession sought and obtained de facto insurance in the form of regulatory capture. 50 Regulatory capture occurs when a government regulator, ostensibly acting in the public interest, furthers the interests of firms being regulated rather than the beneficiaries of the regulation. Applying the regulatory capture insight to financial institutions, the argument would be that financial institutions effectively buy insurance in the form of protective regulation. 51 A possible example of regulatory capture is the ‘banks are different’ rationale that regulators have offered for subsidizing large banks instead of homeowners. 52 There may be sound economic reasons for protecting the payment system that banks provide for the economy, which would include deposit protection, a longstanding form of banking regulation going back to the early 20 th century. 53 But in the application of egalitarian theory to financial regulation post-Great Recession, the interests of lenders and their shareholders and non-depository creditors are entirely instrumental. Financial activity is not an end in itself but an instrument for producing economic well-being in a market oriented economy. If relatively more well-being could be produced by other forms of economic organisation that do not involve financial institutions, then financial institutions would lose the justification for their existence and it would be 50 The classic explanation of regulatory capture is in George Stigler, ‘The Theory of Economic Regulation’, in George Stigler ed., Chicago Studies in Political Economy (University of Chicago Press, 1988), pp. 209-233. 51 A vast literature exists on regulatory capture in the financial industry. See, e.g., Bank of England, ‘Regulators, Financial Industry and the Problem of Regulatory Capture, in Making Good Financial Regulation: Towards a Policy Response to Regulatory Capture (2012); Warwick Commission on International Financial Reform: In Praise of Unlevel Playing Fields, (2009, Ch. 5; Stefano Pagliari ed., Making Good Financial Regulation: Towards a Policy Response to Regulatory Capture (ICFR, 2012); James Kwak, ‘Cultural Capture and the Financial Crisis’, in Daniel Carpenter & David A. Moss, Preventing Regulatory Capture: Special Interest Influence and How to Limit It (Cambridge University Press, 2014), pp. 71-98; Lawrence G. Baxter, ‘”Capture” in Financial Regulation: Can We Channel it Toward the Common Good?’, Cornell Journal of Law and Public Policy 21 (2011), pp. 175-200; 52 Compare Marco Becht, Patrick Bolton & Alisa Röell, ‘Why Bank Governance is Different,’ Oxford Review of Economic Policy 27 (2011), pp. 437-463; Huberto John H. Boyd & Mark Gertler, ‘The Role of Large Banks in the Recent U.S. Banking Crisis’, Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis Quarterly Review (1994), pp. 319–68; Huberto M. Ennis & H.S. Malek, ‘Bank Risk of Failure and the Too-Big- To Fail Policy’, Federal Reserve Bank of Richmond Economic Quarterly 91 (2005), pp. 21-43. 53 Mufi & Sian, n. 19, pp. 119-134. 30 entirely appropriate to liquidate them all and prohibit their activities. 54 The point here is that we do not have to determine what sorts of insurance a lender might want or need in our hypothetical insurance market. At least in egalitarian theory as it is applied here, their interests are subordinate to those of others. The citizen is interested in the public good of economic stability and, if we accept the principal tenets of egalitarian theory, some form of distributive justice in the allocation of resources essential for pursuing one’s life projects. 55 The citizen is an archetype for the average person in a society or the average member of a social contract. Whilst much has been written about distributive justice, the public good of economic stability needs justification. The notion of a public good is from economics. A public good has two essential features: it is non-excludable and non-rivalrous, which means that persons cannot be effectively excluded from use of the good and use by one person does not reduce the availability of the good to others. 56 To insure that the public good of economic stability continues unabated, systemic financial risk and repossession externalities, which we can classify as public bads, need to be mitigated or eliminated. The citizen would want to insure against these public bads. To do this, we would want to monetize the relevant externalities to the extent feasible. The idea would be to give our citizen a right to stability in her economic affairs. The right then could then become a resource to be insured (or traded). Our archetypal 54 Shareholders can invest in other companies. A basic tenet of the efficient capital markets hypothesis in finance is that shareholders do not invest in firms because they ‘like’ a firm. Buying stock is not like buying shoes. Shareholders buy stock because of the particular risk and rate of return for the particular asset class that the stock happens to fall within. If an investment in a bank is no longer profitable compared to other investments, a rational shareholder will sell her bank shares and buy shares in the relatively more profitable investment. Hence the phrase, ‘seen one stock seen em all.’ The efficient capital markets hypothesis has come under some attack in the finance literature but its basic tenets remain true. See Eugene F. Fama, ‘Random Walks in Stock Market Prices’, Financial Analysts Journal, Sept./Oct. 1965; Richard A. Beasley & Stewart C. Myers, Principles of Corporate Finance (McGraw Hill, 2013). 55 The citizen does not care about financial stability per se. Financial stability is simply a route to economic stability. 56 Richard Cornes & Todd Sandler, The Theory of Externalities, Public Goods, and Club Goods (Cambridge University Press, 1996). 31 lender could be required to compensate the citizen for the risk of economic instability. The compensation could be hypothetical in the sense that the lender could be regulated in such a way that alters the distribution of burdens and benefits on lender and citizen, as well as on the borrower and others. We know that in actual capital markets, excessive volatility in asset prices is not actually priced into the market and not something that can be covered by actual insurance. 57 But in our hypothetical insurance market, a rational citizen behind the veil of ignorance would likely want to insure economic stability but minimize restrictions on borrowing by deserving borrowers in need of adequate housing. The citizen would want decent levels of adequate housing to be covered because the citizen does not know her position in the housing market and would want to insure a basic minimum for herself. Minimally adequate housing is a resource that is essential for a decent life. As well, the citizen would want others to have adequate housing, given the substantial benefits to society of people living stable lives in homes they own. The citizen would likely insure its right to stability to the point of reasonable economic prosperity and to avoid severe economic declines and volatility in the housing market. It would likely insure to reduce the risks of the public bads to some reasonably acceptable level, subject to the proviso that no vulnerable group would bear disproportionate burdens. The final step is to transform the results of the hypothetical insurance process into government policy. Recall Dworkin’s point that rights to resources are ‘fixed politically’. 58 As explained above, the borrower would insure against loss of adequate housing, risky crisis-prone economic conditions, disproportionate risk bearing on its mortgage, and undeserved benefits to others from its bad brute luck in home ownership. The citizen would look to minimize the public bads of economic 57 Wyplosz, n. 33, p. 157. 58 Dworkin, n. 28, p. 65. 32 instability from severe decline in home values and other economic shocks. Any number of policy recommendations could flow from these results, but one overriding result seems to be that borrowers and other vulnerable groups should not bear disproportionate burdens when policies are designed to mitigate or eliminate systemic financial risk and the externalities of economic crises. I call this the priority of risk assignment principle. It can be stated in shorthand as follows: Law and public policy to prevent or mitigate the effects of economic crises, when those crises relate to volatility in the financial system, should be designed to avoid imposing unreasonable burdens on persons who, as a result of bad brute luck, have not acted in ways to deserve the imposition of those burdens upon them. It is doubtful that governments have applied something like a priority of risk assignment principle when devising law and policy to mitigate or eliminate the risks under consideration here. Policies developed in early efforts to stabilise economies were morally problematic at best. 59 They included massive subsidizing of banks that were considered ‘too big to fail’ and little if any relief for borrowers. In fact many borrowers were made worse off because of the severe tightening of credit for borrowers least able to afford mortgages. 60 This is a policy of reverse-prioritarianism, based on a priority for the better off. Policies that came later are not much better. As an example, consider the UK’s Mortgage Market Review (MMR), which imposed obligations on lenders to assess the 59 This is not sound economic policy, though it is the one that was selected by the U.S. government and other governments. See Mian & Sufi, n. 19, 119-134. 60 See Emilios Avgouleas, Governance of Global Financial Markets: The Law, the Economics, the Politics (Cambridge University Press, 2012); Kathleen Kahle & Rene M. Stulz, ‘Access to Capital, Investment, and the Financial Crisis’, Journal of Financial Economics 110 (2010), pp. 280-299; Atif Mian, Amir Sufi, & Francesco Trebbi, ‘The Political Economy of the U.S. Mortgage Default Crisis’, American Economic Review 100 (2010), pp. 67-98; Pietro Veronesi & Luigi Zingales, ‘Paulson’s Gift’, Journal of Financial Economics 97 (2010), pp. 339-368; Stephen G. Checchetti, ‘Crisis and Responses: The Federal Reserve in the Early Stages of the Financial Crisis’, Journal of Economic Perspectives 23 (2009), pp. 51-75. 33 affordability of mortgages as a condition for mortgage approval. 61 The US Dodd Frank Act imposes similar ‘ability to pay’ obligations. 62 Imposing affordability requirements may reduce repossession externalities but at a substantial cost to a fair distribution of risk. The lenders will simply pass on the costs of prevention embedded in the affordability requirement to borrowers. Banks will do this by increasing rates of interest to compensate for risk, their traditional method for dealing with increased borrower risk, though they may not need to resort to this with strict affordability requirements. It is unlikely that they would go so far as to use the risky mortgage terms and conditions found in subprime mortgaging, such as balloon payments, or even interest only mortgages on an extensive basis, as these methods (quite rightly) are now very tightly restricted. Regrettably, they will reduce their costs by reducing the pool of potential borrowers. The costs they are limiting are the costs of lending in the form of risk of liability for lending to those unable to afford mortgages. The affordability requirements attempt to internalise the costs of the public bads onto banks, but banks will simply shift these costs onto consumers least able to afford loans and in need of such loans in many cases. Our deserving first time, young families, and lower income homebuyers will be unable to enter the housing market. With the decline in home ownership comes reduction in the benefits of home ownership to communities and the elimination of largest single source of wealth for individuals in societies with significant private home ownership. 63 The affordability 61 Mortgage Market Review (Conduct of Business) Instrument 2012, 27 Sept. 2012; Mortgage Market Review Feedback on CP11/31 and final rules (0ct. 2012). The Financial Conduct Authority is preparing to implement the EU Mortgage Credit Directive, 2014/17/EU, 4 Feb. 2014. 62 John Pottow, ‘Ability to Pay’, Berkeley Business Law Journal 8 (2011), pp. 175-208. 63 Karl E. Case, John M. Quigley, & Robert J. Shiller Jr., ‘Comparing Wealth Effects: The Stock Market versus the Housing Market’, Advances in Macroeconomics 5 (2005). Compare Charles Calomiris, Stanley D. Longhofer & William Miles, ‘The (Mythical?) Housing Wealth Effect’, NBER Working Paper No. 15075, June 2009. The relationship of housing and wealth to inequality is substantial. Research in the UK tends to focus on geographical and intergenerational inequality between regions. The Mortgage Market Review Equality Impact Assessment states tbat ‘no concerns were identified’ for racial equality. Mortgage Market Review, Feedback on CP11/31 and final rules 34 rules have only recently been promulgated and empirical studies will soon be needed to assess impact. Bank balance sheets should however improve, with fewer but higher quality mortgage loans on the books. Affordability policies by themselves are problematic but they may be coupled with other policies to decrease burdens on vulnerable populations. Governments could, for example, combine affordability requirements with assistance to particular groups of persons who have traditionally experienced difficulties in meeting affordability requirements, such as first time homebuyers. The UK government has, for example, put in place a ‘Help to Buy’ loan scheme to provide £9.7 billion to help eligible applicants into home ownership, as well as subsidies to the construction sector. 64 It is too early to assess the effectiveness of these schemes. Critics argue that help to buy programmes cause the very risk they try to alleviate, in particular systemic risk flowing from upward volatility in house prices, or so-called housing bubbles. These concerns are likely to be exaggerated because help to buy does not exist in isolation but is combined with restrictions on mortgage lending such as affordability requirements and with subsidies to the construction sector to build new homes. They also account for a fraction of the housing market. It is beyond egalitarian theory, however, to critically assess these economic effects. A way around these criticisms would be to fundamentally alter the terms of the mortgage contract. A mortgage is debt and with debt comes an inflexible set of fixed claims of creditors on debtors. Debt is conceptually oppositional to insurance at its root. Atif Mian and Amir Sufi argue that ‘debt is the anti-insurance. Instead of helping to share the risks associated with home ownership, it concentrates the risks on those (Oct. 2012, at A5:5. Substantial US research shows a link between housing and wealth inequality and race and ethnicity. See e.g., Lauren J. Krivo & Robert L. Kaufman, ‘The Relationship of Housing and Wealth Inequality to Race and Ethnicity, Demography 41 (2004), pp. 585-608. 64 http://www.helptobuy.org.uk 35 least able to afford it’. 65 By this they refer to what happens when house prices experience a steep decline in an economic crisis. As explained above, the mortgage contract places all risk of housing value declines on the borrower, the person usually most deserving of help and least deserving of shouldering all of this risk. As Mian and Sufi explain: When house prices in the aggregate collapse by 20 percent, the losses are concentrated on the borrowers in the economy. Given that borrowers already had low net worth before the crash (which is why they needed to borrow), the concentration of losses on them devastates their financial condition. They already had very little net worth – now they have even less. 66 The situation they describe differs fundamentally from the way that insurance operates. In an insurance context, the losses would be ‘covered’ in the sense that the insurance would compensate the borrower for the loss. In the hypothetical insurance market worked out above, the borrower would want to be insured against the catastrophic loss associated with the loss of her home as a result of an economic crisis. In contrast to the loss that the borrower incurs in the face of steep declines in housing values, the lender suffers significantly less. As Mian and Sufi explain, using the concept of ‘savers’ to represent the claims underlying those of the Lender: In contrast [to the substantial losses borrowers incur in a collapse of housing prices], the savers, who typically have a lot of financial assets and little mortgage debt, experience a much less severe decline in their net worth when house prices fall. This is because they ultimately own – through their deposits, bonds, and equity holdings – the senior claims on houses in the economy. 67 Mian and Sufi advocate a ‘shared responsibility mortgage’ or SRM, a hybrid concept with features of both debt and equity. 68 While the UK mortgage market is 65 Mian & Sufi, n. 19, p. 30. 66 Ibid., p. 19. 67 Ibid. 68 Ibid., pp. 171-174. 36 overwhelmingly in adjustable rate mortgages, which soften the blow to borrowers in economic declines, because interest rates decline as well in such periods, an SRM goes further. An SRM would be linked to a local house price index. If house prices rise or remain the same as when the mortgage was entered, the monthly mortgage payment stays the same as does the mortgage amortization schedule. If the house price index falls below the level it was when the borrower entered into the mortgage, the monthly mortgage payment reduces but the mortgage amortization schedule remains the same. This results in an automatic but temporary reduction of the mortgage principal. It is temporary because house prices tend to increase the longer the time period in which they are considered. So, when the local house price index increases, the mortgage payment and principal will revert to its initial state. To eliminate or reduce the possibility that the lender will increase mortgage interest rates to compensate for its risk in sharing the downside potential of the housing market, the SRM could give the lender, say, a five percent share of the capital gain when the home is sold or refinanced. The SRM is just one policy proposal that seems to comply with the luck egalitarian requirements set forth in the priority of risk assignment principle. Others are possible. It is beyond our scope here to exhaustively identify these options, but rather to elucidate why such options are necessary to achieve just results in the markets for mortgage credit. Conclusion This paper deals with one of the most complex areas of human interaction. What makes systemic financial risk even more difficult to take on in philosophy is that the workings of financial markets tend to be fully understood only by a relatively small number of specialists in economics, finance, and law. Financial markets are, however, 37 totally of our doing. We create them. Our social practices and our actions determine who gets what, who loses, and who gains. I have made what I consider to be an early first step in seeking to understand how persons should act when they are part of large groups of people making financial choices beneficial to each of them individually but substantially harmful to many others. In addition, we want to know how to distribute the systemic financial risk associated with these individual actions. To date, the overwhelming focus of inquiry has been in economics and finance, disciplines that have not traditionally focused on egalitarian concerns. I have attempted to steer this debate towards a discussion of the distributive implications of law and policy, looking to luck egalitarian theory to provide some tentative answers, with a focus on the paradigmatic transaction, that of buying a home with a mortgage that many individuals, often vulnerable, have to deal with if they are to pursue their life projects. Luck egalitarianism, I contend, offers substantial promise in helping societies reach consensus on how to allocate the burdens and benefits of financial regulation designed to mitigate or eliminate systemic financial risk. work_6poanjsjbjesnc4m3uutnjadxi ---- title Edinburgh Research Explorer Justice and Home Affairs Citation for published version: Walker, N & Newman, K 1998, 'Justice and Home Affairs', International and Comparative Law Quarterly, vol. 47, pp. 231-38. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0020589300061650 Digital Object Identifier (DOI): 10.1017/S0020589300061650 Link: Link to publication record in Edinburgh Research Explorer Document Version: Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Published In: International and Comparative Law Quarterly Publisher Rights Statement: ©Walker, N., & Newman, K. (1998). Justice and Home Affairs. International and Comparative Law Quarterly, 47, 231-38doi: 10.1017/S0020589300061650 General rights Copyright for the publications made accessible via the Edinburgh Research Explorer is retained by the author(s) and / or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing these publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Take down policy The University of Edinburgh has made every reasonable effort to ensure that Edinburgh Research Explorer content complies with UK legislation. If you believe that the public display of this file breaches copyright please contact openaccess@ed.ac.uk providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 06. Apr. 2021 https://doi.org/10.1017/S0020589300061650 https://doi.org/10.1017/S0020589300061650 https://www.research.ed.ac.uk/portal/en/publications/justice-and-home-affairs(935a0ff5-e54f-4791-b852-afe761a93f6c).html http://journals.cambridge.orgDownloaded: 20 Dec 2013 IP address: 129.215.19.194 JANUARY 1998] Current Developments: EC Law 231 also extends the Vlassopoulou recognition of qualifications4' (and not just pro- fessional experience as now) to those falling under these directives. Another case, Aranitis,'* has recently given rise to a most significant judgment on mutual recognition.65 Georgios Aranitis held a Greek diploma, "Ptichiouchos Geologjkos", which is awarded after four years of university studies in geology. He had worked as a geologist in Greece for over a decade. He then moved to Berlin where he wished to carry on working as a geologist. The local employment office in Berlin classified him as an "unskilled assistant". He challenged this classification, relying on the general directive on mutual recognition of professional qualifi- cations. The Arbtitsamt allowed him a literal translation of his Greek title, but refused to allow him to use the equivalent German qualification Diplom-Geo- loge.** The main distinction between the Greek and German qualification was the requirement in Germany of a dissertation." The profession of geologist was not considered to be regulated in Germany and the German authorities thus con- sidered that Aranitis was unable to rely on the mutual recognition directive. The Court agreed, observing that "whether or not a profession is regulated depends on the legal situation in the host member State and not on the conditions prevailing on the employment market in that member State".** But the Court went on to indicate" that Aranitis should, nevertheless, be able to rely on the Vlassopoulou jurisprudence which it extended to cover qualifications for unregulated occu- pations which could help holders gain employment. Thus, should an element of knowledge or ability not be attested to in Aranitis's Greek qualification the Ger- man authorities could refuse such recognition unless his practical or other aca- demic experience compensated for the deficit. It seems that the general case law has been extended to require competent authorities to assess the equivalence of the academic qualifications and, if missing elements are found, then experience, knowledge and ability subsequently acquired should be taken into account Con- fusion over qualifications could be averted by a tag indicating the qualification of origin. JULIAN LONBAY* II. JUSTICE AND H O M E A F F A IRS T H E addition of "Justice and Home Affairs" (JHA) to the list of subjects covered in Current Developments reflects the growing significance of this area of 63. See Lonbay (1992) 41I.C.L.Q. 212,215. 64. Case C-164/94 Georgios Aranitis v. Land Berlin [19%] E.C.R. 1-135. 65. The following analysis follows that used in J. Lonbay, "The Mutual Recognition of Professional Qualifications in the E C , in Hodgin et aL, Professional Liability: Law and Insurance (19%) Chap.l. 66. As Advocate General Leger stated, the Directive should not be used to "turn truth upside down by allowing persons who do not possess a certain diploma to make use of a diploma which they do not have": supra n.64, at para.45. 67. Report of the bearing: Sitzungsberichi, pp.2-3.1 am grateful to Alex Bosch for trans- lating this for me. 68. Supra n.64, at para23. 69. Idem, parasJO-32. * Director of the Institute of European Law, University of Birmingham. http://journals.cambridge.org http://journals.cambridge.orgDownloaded: 20 Dec 2013 IP address: 129.215.19.194 232 International and Comparative Law Quarterly [VOL. 47 European law and policy within the overall Treaty framework. In this introduc- tory note, a brief account is given of the history of co-operation between EU mem- ber States in JHA matters, culminating in the significant changes announced in the Treaty of Amsterdam in October 1997. It is a historical record which is marked by discontinuity and institutional complexity, full justice to which would require detailed analysis.1 Here we confine ourselves instead to a broad-brush approach, seeking to highlight the main themes which have characterised JHA co-operation. In future notes particular areas and issues of current interest will be examined more closely. A. Before Maastricht Prior to the conclusion of the Treaty on European Union (TEU) at Maastricht in 1992 there was no formal recognition of JHA within the EC Treaty framework. Areas such as policing, criminal justice and immigration tended to be viewed as far removed from the economic core of Community activity. Further, as home affairs were traditionally regarded as closely bound up with the security and sovereignty of the nation State, the possibility of encroachment by a supranational organis- ation such as the European Community was jealously guarded against3 Yet as economic integration encouraged closer social and cultural ties across the Com- munity, the member States increasingly came to view modest co-operation in a number of JHA matters as mutually beneficial. Because of national sensibilities, however, such co-operation could only take place in the shadow of the Treaties. This informal activity may be seen as a series of discrete policy-making threads which, from the mid-1980s onwards, began to be woven together to form a coher- ent pattern.3 Two important early initiatives were provided by the Trevi and Schengen sys- tems. From 1975 onwards, Trevi served as an intergovernmental forum for mem- ber States to develop common measures, first in respect of counter-terrorism and latterly concerning drugs, organised crime, police training and technology and a range of other policing matters.4 Schengen was established with a wider remit but initially was restricted to a smaller group of States. The initial Schengen Agree- ment of 19853 paved the way for abolition of border controls between France, Germany and the Benelux countries. A more detailed Implementation Agree- ment of 1 990' established a number of related law-enforcement measures includ- 1. See e.g. R. Biebcr and J. Monar (Eds), Justice and Home Affairs in the European Union (1995); D . Cullen, J. Monar and P. Myers (Eds), Co-operation in Justice and Home Affairs: An Evaluation of the Third Pillar in Practice (1996); M. Anderson, M. den Boer, P. Cullen, W. C Gilmore, C D . Raab and N. Walker, Policing The European Union: Theory, Law and Practice (1995). 2. See N. Walker, "Policing the European Union: The Politics of Transition", in O. Marenin (Ed.), Policing Change, Changing Police (1996). 3. For a more detailed analysis, see J. Benyon, L. Turnbull, A. Willis, R. Woodward and A. Beck, Police Co-operation in Europe: An Investigation (1993). 4. Idem, pp.152-167. 5. A text in English is reproduced as an annex to H. Schemers et al (eds). Free Move- ment of Persons in Europe (1995), pp.547-551. 6. Idem, pp-552-605. http://journals.cambridge.org http://journals.cambridge.orgDownloaded: 20 Dec 2013 IP address: 129.215.19.194 JANUARY 1998] Current Developments: EC Law 233 ing a computerised information system (Schengen Information System) and police co-operation. More broadly, it made provision for the development of com- mon policies on asylum and illegal immigration. Of the many other early developments in JHA co-operation, two stand out. First, there is immigration and the related matters of asylum and visa policy and practice. In the 1970s and 1980s there was a running dispute between the Com- mission and the member States over the competence of the Community to pro- ceed by supranational means, in particular by means of directives and decisions, as opposed to the more informal, State-centred method of intergovernmental co- operation. On the whole, the latter view prevailed, a position reinforced by the establishment in 1986 of the Ad Hoc Group on Immigration. Progress within the framework of the Community was also largely frustrated in the area of judicial co-operation in matters of criminal law. The work of the EC member States was consistently overshadowed by that of the larger regional organisation—the Council of Europe, which generated a substantial body of inter- national criminal legislation in the post-war years.7 A bold plan by Giscard D'Es- taing in the late 1970s to develop a common "European Judicial Space" across the Community ultimately foundered on its own excessive ambition, and criminal law and procedure duly remained outside EC competence. One casualty of this failure was a more modest intergovernmental steering group—the European Political Co-operation (EPC) Judicial Co-operation Working Group (JCWG)—although it was eventually reconstituted in the mid-1980s. Renewed impetus was given to the activities of a number of these agencies with the development in 1985 of the Commission's "1992" single market programme. If its deadline was to be honoured, co-ordination would be required over a wide range of matters, including the strand of single market policy most closely associ- ated with JHA—the free movement of persons. As the vehicle of an integrationist inner core of member States which wished to accelerate progress in this area, the Schengen system was a direct result of the 1992 initiative. Within the Community itself, the Co-ordinators Group on the Free Movement of Persons was established in 1988 to oversee the measures necessary to implement the 1992 programme in this area.' The Co-ordinators Group set out its manifesto in the "Palma Document",' which sought to justify the expansion of Community interest into new areas by arguing that the effective functioning of the Community post-1992 demanded that the member States adopt a number of compensatory measures in response to the anticipated loss of national security consequential upon the abolition of internal frontier controls. These should include new measures to tackle international ter- rorism, drug-trafficking and other illegal trade, improved police and judicial co- operation, and—in pursuit of a strengthened external frontier in lieu of internal controls—the development of a common visa and of uniform asylum policies. 7. See Anderson a al, op. cti. supra n.l, at cfaap.7. 8. Idem, chap.4. 9. Reproduced as App.5 to the Report of the House of Lords Select Committee on the European Communities, "1992; Border Controls of People"; Session 1988-89,22nd Report ( H X . Papers 90). http://journals.cambridge.org http://journals.cambridge.orgDownloaded: 20 Dec 2013 IP address: 129.215.19.194 234 International and Comparative Law Quarterly [VOL. 47 As well as providing more ambitious terms of reference for existing bodies such as Trevi and the JCWG, the Palma Document and the political climate which sur- rounded it also stimulated the development of new forms of co-operation. These included, most notably, the Mutual Assistance Group 1992 (MAG 92), which ad- dressed the implications of free movement for European customs agencies, and the European Committee to Combat Drugs (CELAD), established in 1990 to develop and co-ordinate preventive and repressive anti-drugs strategies among member States. B. The Third Pillar The Treaty on European Union (TEU) accorded formal recognition to this bur- geoning area of activity by providing a separate title on co-operation in Justice and Home Affairs. This quickly became know as the third pillar, in recognition of the fact that the Treaty structure now encompassed not only the central (or first) pillar of European Community law, but also two flanking pillars dealing with Common Foreign and Security Policy (second pillar) and JHA respectively. The third pillar sought to integrate the various areas of JHA co-operation and the various levels of personnel through an elaborate structure, spanning five lev- els. At the apex is the Justice and Home Affairs Council, which comprises minis- ters from the member States and which acts as the supreme policy-making body. Situated immediately below the JHA Council is COREPER, where permanent representatives from the member States negotiate and agree agendas on behalf of JHA ministers. Below these two familiar Community organs lies the K4 Com- mittee, which is the direct institutional successor to the Co-ordinators Group. The K4 Committee has in turn generated a network of sub-groups which provide the fourth and fifth levels of the hierarchy. Three comitis directeurs (CDs) report to K4. CD I is concerned with immigration and asylum, absorbing the functions of the pre-Maastricht Ad Hoc Group on Immigration. CD II is concerned with police and customs co-operation, replacing Trevi and extending the MAG initiative. CD III is concerned with judicial co-operation of a criminal and civil nature, taking over the work of the JCWG. Finally, each steering group has a number of sub- committees, or working groups, which have emerged gradually since the basic framework was put in place. These working groups presently number around 20, ranging from general flagship concerns, such as terrorism, police co-operation and external frontiers, to more detailed policy areas such as false travel documents and the international enforcement of driving disqualifications.10 These structural arrangements are a peculiar hybrid, reflecting continuing ambivalence about the appropriate degree of international control over internal security matters. They are not "pure intergovernmental co-operation"," since Community institutions are involved at a number of points; but neither are they part of EC law in the same way as the first pillar, since the Community continues to lack direct legislative competence in JHA matters and, more generally, the bal- ance of influence between Community institutions and members States in the pol- icy process continues to favour the latter. 10. For more detailed analysis see Anderson etaL,op.dL supra n.l, at chap.2. 11. D. O'Keefe, -Recasting the Third Pillar" (1995) 32 CMJ.R. 893,902. http://journals.cambridge.org http://journals.cambridge.orgDownloaded: 20 Dec 2013 IP address: 129.215.19.194 JANUARY 1998] Current Developments: EC Law 235 In the absence of any direct legislative competence, the Council nevertheless has various types of decision-making authority under the third pillar, namely joint positions, joint actions and conventions.12 While the development of such instru- ments is an important advance, doubts remain over their efficacy. Joint positions and joint actions mirror the position under the second pillar (Foreign and Security Policy), but are less obviously suited to a domain which by its nature requires "legislative action rather than external posture"." Further, they are subject to the requirement of Council unanimity, thereby ensuring that progress can be made only at the pace of the most reluctant member State. Third pillar conventions occupy the firmer legal ground of classical public international law, but they require not only unanimity within the Council but also ratification by all member States in accordance with their domestic constitutional requirements. Such a "double-lock" procedure represents a formidable obstacle. Finally, thepassarelle provision, which allows a transfer of competence from third to first pillar in respect of the majority of JHA matters, offers opportunities for effective EU enactments, but it too is guarded by the double-lock.14 A similarly mixed picture emerges from an examination of the relevant institu- tional competences. The Commission "shall be fully associated with" the work of the third pillar. Yet in contrast to its role under the first pillar, the Commission does not enjoy exclusive power of initiative. Instead, it shares this right with the member States in most areas and, as regards judicial co-operation in criminal mat- ters, customs co-operation and police co-operation, it has no right of initiative whatsoever.15 The European Parliament is consulted on "principal aspects of [JHA] activities", yet, while it may also ask questions of the Council and make recommendations to it,16 the Parliament lacks the significant role in the law-mak- ing process and in the monitoring of executive power which it has gradually acquired under the first pillar. As for the Court of Justice, it has no inherent juris- diction under the third pillar, but it may be given powers under specific third pillar conventions to interpret their provisions and rule on disputes." So far, however, the vesting of jurisdiction in the Court under particular conventions has proved deeply controversial and has led to delays in their ratification and implementation.w While it marks a qualitative shift from the informality of the pre-Maastricht era, the third pillar has tended to attract two kinds of criticism. On the one hand, it has been criticised as ineffectual; as an unduly complex and cumbersome framework 12. Art.KJ(2) TEU. 13. J. Monar. "European Union—Justice and Home Affaire A Balance Sheet and an Agenda for Reform", in G. Edwards and A. Pijpers (Eds), The Politics of European Treaty Reform: The 1996 Intergovernmental Conference and Beyond (1997), pp326-339, at p330. 14. ATLK.9TEU. 15. ArtK.4(2) TEU. 16. ATLK.6TEU. 17. ArtJC3{2) TEU. 18. The most controversial example to date has been the Europol Convention (1995) O J. C316. After its conclusion in July 1995. ratification and implementation were delayed pend- ing an agreement on the role of the ECJ. When the matter was finally resolved in the form of a Protocol to the European Convention in July 1996, it effectively took the form of an agree- ment to differ, with each high contracting party retaining the option to accept the jurisdiction of the ECJ to interpret the Convention by means of a declaration to that effect. http://journals.cambridge.org http://journals.cambridge.orgDownloaded: 20 Dec 2013 IP address: 129.215.19.194 236 International and Comparative Law Quarterly [ V O L . 4 7 whose early record suggests that it will be unable to deliver significant results. In particular, it is claimed that progress on the conclusion and ratification of conven- tions—the highest legal instrument under the third pillar—has been slow and uneven; and as regards other less formal decision-making mechanisms, although joint actions have become increasingly popular, joint positions have been almost entirely neglected, and there has been a tendency to fall back instead upon classi- cal non-binding measures of intergovernmental action such as resolutions, state- ments and conclusions." On the other hand, the third pillar has also been criticised as being unduly authoritarian in its policy orientation. On this view, it has demon- strated an excessive concern with repressive instruments of security and order. Arguably, these two criticisms have a common root in the continuing preoccu- pation of member States with the retention of sovereignty in JH A matters. If the third pillar is cumbersome and slow, it is at least in part because the reluctance to move towards taking decisions by majority votes leads to progress within the third pillar being determined by the most cautious member State. Equally, if the third pillar is unduly committed to a narrow security perspective, it is because sover- eignty concerns continue to militate against the full involvement of supranational institutions, like the Parliament and the Court of Justice, no matter how well placed they may be to check and monitor third pillar activities and safeguard indi- vidual freedoms.2" C. "Maastricht II"—The Amsterdam Treaty These criticisms gained momentum during the period leading up to the 1996 Inter- Governmental Conference (IGC), with all the European institutions, including the normally sceptical Council, admitting that there was a case for greater involve- ment of EC institutions to improve effectiveness and accountability.21 These con- cerns were crystallised in the Reflection Group report of December 1995 which served as the agenda for the IGC, and ultimately, in the Treaty of Amsterdam itself. The Treaty, when ratified, will undoubtedly signal a new step towards the inte- gration of JHA matters within the mainstream of European law. However, because of continuing disagreement between member States as to the speed and direction of JHA activity, the legislative strategy chosen to bring about this further integration is marked by complexity and qualification. Under the umbrella of a new chapter on the so-called "area of freedom, security and justice"22 are to be found both a new EC Treaty Title on visas, asylum, immigration and other policies related to free movement of persons23 and a revised and streamlined Title VI of the TEU covering police and customs co-operation and judicial co-operation in crimi- 19. See e.g. Monar, op. at supra n.13: B. Meyring, "Intergovernmentalism and Supra- nationality: Two Stereotypes for a Complex Reality" (1997) E.l_Rev. 221. 20. See e.g. D. Bigo, "The European Internal Security Field", in M. Anderson and M. den Boer (Eds), Policing Across National Boundaries (1994), pp.161-173; M. Spencer, Stales of Injustice: A Guide to Human Rights and Civil Liberties in the European Union (1995). 21. See Monar, op. at. supra n.13. 22. The present note refers only briefly to the relevant provisions of the new Treaty. A more detailed analysis of these provisions in so far as they relate to the free movement of persons will be provided in a subsequent note by Julian Lombay. 23. New Title Ilia, Art73i-q. http://journals.cambridge.org http://journals.cambridge.orgDownloaded: 20 Dec 2013 IP address: 129.215.19.194 JANUARY 1998] Current Developments: EC Law 237 nal matters. Accordingly, JHA matters no longer have a single Treaty source, but now straddle the first and third pillars. Superimposed upon this dual structure is the incorporation of the entire Schengen acquis.1* This represents a significant pol- itical victory for the Schengen system and its expanding membership, which now includes all EU member States except the United Kingdom and Ireland, together with Norway and Iceland as associate members. In turn, this new JHA system will allow for flexibility and a wide variety of involvement by member States. The United Kingdom and Ireland are allowed to maintain their existing border controls,23 and need take no part in the adoption by the Council of measures pursuant to the new EC Title on free movement, asylum and immigration.26 Equally, they may opt out of those existing or new parts of the Schengen acquis which fall within the third pillar.27 Denmark is not required to adopt those parts of the Schengen acquis which are determined to be part of the new EC Title, although it has no such exemption in respect of those part of the Schengen acquis which fall within the third pillar.28 There are also flexible arrange- ments for Iceland and Norway, which are to be involved in the deliberations of the JHA Council and be bound by its decisions, but only in matters, under either first or third pillar, which form part of the Schengen acquis." Finally, in addition to these particular provisions, the new third pillar strengthens the facility in the Maastricht Treaty for any number of member States to "establish closer co-oper- ation" on any matter.* Arguably, the new arrangements go some way to increasing both the efficiency and the accountability of JHA co-operation. Matters which were previously located within the third pillar or within Schengen have been transferred to the first pillar, so that majority voting and parliamentary and judicial supervision associ- ated with the latter will now be available. Even within the streamlined third pillar, there is some strengthening of the role of the EC institutions. The consultative role of the Parliament is clarified-" in respect of conventions and two other new policy instruments under the draft Treaty—"framework decisions" made "for the pur- pose of approximation of the laws and regulations of the Member States" and other non-legislative "decisions";32 the power of the Commission to initiate decision-taking is extended to all third pillar matters;" and for the first time gen- eral provision is made for the jurisdiction of the Court (a) to give preliminary rulings on the interpretation of conventions and on the validity and interpretation 24. Protocol Integrating the Schengen Acquis Into the Framework of the European Union. 25. Protocol on the Application of Certain Aspects of Article 7a of the Treaty Estab- lishing the European Community to the United Kingdom and to Ireland. 26. Protocol on the Position of the United Kingdom and Ireland. 27. Protocol, supra n.24, Arts.4-5. 28. Protocol on the Position of Denmark. 29. Protocol, supra n.24, Art.6. 30. The further development of this provision under the Amsterdam Treaty, replacing the existing Art.K.7 with new Arts. 12, IS and 16 TEU, allows member States to make use of Community mechanisms, institutions and procedures in the furtherance of co-operation. 31. N e w A r t K l l T E U . 32. Under the new Treaty, joint actions and joint positions are both abolished, to be replaced by framework decisions, decisions, and common positions; see new Art.K.6 TEU. 33. NewArLK6TEU. http://journals.cambridge.org http://journals.cambridge.orgDownloaded: 20 Dec 2013 IP address: 129.215.19.194 238 International and Comparative Law Quarterly [VOL. 47 of measures implementing them, and also of the new decisions and framework decisions (albeit this jurisdiction does not apply in respect of any member State until it has made a declaration accepting it); (b) to review the legality of framework decisions and decisions in actions brought by a member State or the Commission; and (c) to rule on disputes between member States or between member States and the Commission on the application of the various policy instruments.*4 Whatever progress there has been, however, has been at the cost of uniformity. In the words of one commentator, the new institutional landscape is "frighteningly indeterminate",13 and this may cause problems which outweigh the benefits of par- tial transfer to the first pillar and strengthening of the residual third pillar. The benefits of a co-ordinated approach across member States and the various JHA policy sectors (which was one of the main arguments for the introduction of the third pillar at Maastricht) are endangered by the introduction of variable geometry within the Treaty framework. The membership of JHA Council and its supporting bureaucracy and operations will be constituted differently for different tasks with no guarantee that its various strategic agendas or policy initiatives will be mutually complementary. Even within particular policy fields, the right of indi- vidual member States to refuse the jurisdiction of the Court suggests that tensions and conflict over the terms of co-operation may emerge. Further, increased insti- tutional complexity may make the already intricate system of JHA co-operation even less transparent and less easily understood by the European public, and so less amenable to genuine democratic involvement and accountability. Of course, this is not to deny that some variable geometry was required at Amsterdam if member States ideologically divided over the acceptable limits of further integration were to avail themselves of mechanisms for deepening their commitment to joint action wherever the will existed. Neither should the possi- bility be dismissed that measures currently taken by the integrationist core will set a standard to which all member States will aspire in due course. In the shorter term, however, as regards the likelihood of its increasing co-operative efficiency and democratic responsiveness in JHA matters, "one step forward and two steps backward" would appear to be the verdict on the new Treaty. NEIL WALKER* 34. N e w A r t K . 7 T E U . 35. Professor Dierdre Curtin, in a lecture to the Annual Congress of the Academy on European Law in Trier, 20 June 1997; quoted in Statewatch, VoL7, N o 3 (May-June, 1997), p.18. • Professor of Legal and Constitutional Theory, University of Aberdeen. http://journals.cambridge.org work_6qoe2jzbmjcjfkmj4hdi6bpany ---- Distributive Justice and CEO Compensation econstor Make Your Publications Visible. A Service of zbw Leibniz-Informationszentrum Wirtschaft Leibniz Information Centre for Economics Jasso, Guillermina; Meyersson Milgrom, Eva M. Working Paper Distributive justice and CEO compensation IZA Discussion Papers, No. 3236 Provided in Cooperation with: IZA – Institute of Labor Economics Suggested Citation: Jasso, Guillermina; Meyersson Milgrom, Eva M. (2007) : Distributive justice and CEO compensation, IZA Discussion Papers, No. 3236, Institute for the Study of Labor (IZA), Bonn This Version is available at: http://hdl.handle.net/10419/35019 Standard-Nutzungsbedingungen: Die Dokumente auf EconStor dürfen zu eigenen wissenschaftlichen Zwecken und zum Privatgebrauch gespeichert und kopiert werden. Sie dürfen die Dokumente nicht für öffentliche oder kommerzielle Zwecke vervielfältigen, öffentlich ausstellen, öffentlich zugänglich machen, vertreiben oder anderweitig nutzen. Sofern die Verfasser die Dokumente unter Open-Content-Lizenzen (insbesondere CC-Lizenzen) zur Verfügung gestellt haben sollten, gelten abweichend von diesen Nutzungsbedingungen die in der dort genannten Lizenz gewährten Nutzungsrechte. Terms of use: Documents in EconStor may be saved and copied for your personal and scholarly purposes. You are not to copy documents for public or commercial purposes, to exhibit the documents publicly, to make them publicly available on the internet, or to distribute or otherwise use the documents in public. If the documents have been made available under an Open Content Licence (especially Creative Commons Licences), you may exercise further usage rights as specified in the indicated licence. www.econstor.eu IZA DP No. 3236 Distributive Justice and CEO Compensation Guillermina Jasso Eva M. Meyersson Milgrom D I S C U S S I O N P A P E R S E R I E S Forschungsinstitut zur Zukunft der Arbeit Institute for the Study of Labor December 2007 Distributive Justice and CEO Compensation Guillermina Jasso New York University and IZA Eva M. Meyersson Milgrom Stanford University Discussion Paper No. 3236 December 2007 IZA P.O. Box 7240 53072 Bonn Germany Phone: +49-228-3894-0 Fax: +49-228-3894-180 E-mail: iza@iza.org Any opinions expressed here are those of the author(s) and not those of the institute. Research disseminated by IZA may include views on policy, but the institute itself takes no institutional policy positions. The Institute for the Study of Labor (IZA) in Bonn is a local and virtual international research center and a place of communication between science, politics and business. IZA is an independent nonprofit company supported by Deutsche Post World Net. The center is associated with the University of Bonn and offers a stimulating research environment through its research networks, research support, and visitors and doctoral programs. IZA engages in (i) original and internationally competitive research in all fields of labor economics, (ii) development of policy concepts, and (iii) dissemination of research results and concepts to the interested public. IZA Discussion Papers often represent preliminary work and are circulated to encourage discussion. Citation of such a paper should account for its provisional character. A revised version may be available directly from the author. mailto:iza@iza.org IZA Discussion Paper No. 3236 December 2007 ABSTRACT Distributive Justice and CEO Compensation* This paper develops a framework for studying individuals’ ideas about what constitutes just compensation for chief executive officers (CEOs) and reports estimates of just CEO pay and the principles guiding ideas of justice. The sample consists of students pursuing a Master of Business Administration (MBA) degree in Sweden and the United States. The framework, based on justice theory and making use of Rossi’s factorial survey method, enables assessment of ideas of fairness in CEO compensation, including (1) the just CEO compensation, in the eyes of each observer; (2) the principles of microjustice – observers’ ideas about “who should get what” based on characteristics of CEOs and their firms; and (3) principles of macrojustice – ideas about the just level and dispersion in compensation across all CEOs. Our estimates yield the following main results: First, there is broad agreement on the median just CEO compensation but substantial inter-individual variation in the principles of microjustice and the other principles of macrojustice. Second, there is remarkable similarity in the distributions of the principles of microjustice and macrojustice across the MBA groups. Other important results include a pervasive gender attentiveness among MBA students and tolerance for large variability in CEO pay. JEL Classification: D31, D6, D8, G30, I3, J16, J31, J33, M14, M52 Keywords: justice theory, fairness, CEO compensation, factorial survey method, MBA students, gender, inequality, Gini coefficient, Atkinson measure, Theil’s inequality measures Corresponding author: Guillermina Jasso Department of Sociology New York University 295 Lafayette Street, 4th Floor New York, NY 10012-9605 USA E-mail: gj1@nyu.edu * Authors listed in alphabetical order. Earlier versions of portions of this paper were presented at the Harvard-MIT Economic Sociology Workshop, Sloan School of Management, 2001; the Sociology Department Colloquium, Stanford University, 2003; the Management Colloquium, City University of Hong Kong, 2004; Symposium on Human Capital and Labour Markets, Zhejiang University, Hangzhou, China, 2004; the annual meeting of the Society for the Advancement of Socio-Economics, Washington, DC, 2004; the annual meeting of the American Sociological Association, San Francisco, California, 2004; the Economics Department at Stockholm University, 2005; and the biennial meeting of the International Society for Justice Research, Berlin, Germany, 2006. We are grateful to participants at those meetings and to colleagues at IZA for many valuable comments and suggestions. We also gratefully acknowledge the intellectual and financial support of the Bechtel Foundation, New York University, the Sloan School of Management at MIT, the Stockholm Institute of Business, and Stanford University. This paper is forthcoming in Acta Sociologica. mailto:gj1@nyu.edu 1 1. INTRODUCTION Recent increases in inequality in many countries of the world appear due to the increasing concentration of wealth at the top; and the increasing concentration of wealth at the top is in turn widely attributed to a new phenomenon in economic life, namely, very high-earning salaried workers, in particular, chief executive officers (Atkinson and Piketty 2006; Piketty and Saez 2006; Roine and Waldenström 2006). Wealth and inequality awaken justice concerns. Substantial gaps between what people think is just and what they see around them generate judgments of injustice, setting in motion a train of negative consequences for individual and society (Bok 1993). Of course, ideas of justice may differ across individuals and across societies and their subgroups. Elites constitute one potentially important segment of the population, not only because of their decisionmaking activities but also because they may share a global common culture. Students pursuing a Master of Business Administration (MBA) degree are a special group of interest. The MBA students of today are the future CEOs, board members, entrepreneurs, and investors. Thus, their ideas about what is fair compensation, their views of the relevant factors in setting CEO compensation, and their tolerance or intolerance of inequality provide an important glimpse into the societal conversation on matters of compensation and inequality in the years to come. Moreover, to the extent that students come from all over the world, variability within university may reflect the diversity of their origins; across universities and countries, commonality may reflect the emerging global common culture while variability may reflect persistent distinctive ideas of justice and tolerance for inequality (Bok 1993; Kelley and Evans 1993; Master 2002; Söderström et al. 2003; Svallfors 1997; Wegener 1991). In this paper we focus on CEO compensation as viewed by MBA students at two universities, one in Sweden, the other in the United States, asking three main questions: First, what are MBA students’ ideas about fairness in CEO compensation – including not only ideas of the just amounts of pay but also ideas about the just returns to personal and firm characteristics (microjustice) and about the just level and dispersion in CEO pay (macrojustice)? Second, do The words “justice” and “fairness” and their cognates are used interchangeably.1 2 MBA students within a university have a common view about what constitutes just CEO pay, just returns, and just level and dispersion? Third, are these ideas of justice similar across the two universities?1 To address these questions, we develop a framework which is based on justice theory and makes use of Rossi’s factorial survey method, building on early studies of the justice of earnings (Jasso and Rossi 1977) and of elites (Berk and Rossi 1977; Jasso 1988). The framework links observers’ ideas of justice, principles of microjustice, and principles of macrojustice, enabling estimation of these observer-specific quantities and assessment of the mix of agreements and disagreements across respondents. The paper is organized as follows: In Section 2 we describe the framework and its theoretical and empirical background. The method used in the present study is developed in Section 3. Section 4 reports the results. A short discussion concludes the paper. 2. JUSTICE JUDGMENTS OF CEO COMPENSATION: THEORETICAL AND EMPIRICAL BACKGROUND The work reported in this paper builds on and contributes to two research traditions, the first focused on large questions of increasing income inequality and attendant dynamics and the second on fairness concerns. Both converge on executive compensation and elites. The fairness literature suggests that two distinct kinds of principles operate to produce ideas of the just reward: (1) principles of microjustice – ideas about “who should get what” -- and (2) principles of macrojustice – ideas about what the overall distribution should look like (Arts et al. 1991; Berger et al. 1972; Brickman et al. 1981; Jasso 1983). That literature also suggests that ideas of justice are “in the eyes of the beholder” (Walster et al. 1976:4) and thus shaped by the observer’s own characteristics, social location, and societal characteristics (Kelley and Evans 1993; Svallfors 1997; Verwiebe and Wegener 2000). Both literatures highlight the income domain Succinct summary of the larger inequality framework is found in Piketty and Saez2 (2006) and of the justice framework in Jasso and Wegener (1997) and Jasso (1999, 2007). 3 (1) (Arts et al. 1991; Atkinson and Piketty 2006; Bok 1993; Jasso and Rossi 1977; Kelley and Evans 1993; Piketty and Saez 2006).2 2.1. Justice Justice theory identifies four main elements in justice processes. First, individuals and societies form ideas of justice; in the distributive-retributive domain these are ideas about what constitutes the just reward for specified rewardees, who can be self or other. Second, these ideas of justice may be used to help shape actual situations; for example, ideas of the just reward may play a part in salary decisions. Third, individuals judge the justice or injustice of actual situations, generating the justice evaluation; for example, they may judge that one person is overpaid and another underpaid and/or that the pay structure in a firm has unjustly too much inequality. Fourth, the justice evaluations become important determinants of further behaviors, such as lobbying for policies or candidates. This paper is chiefly concerned with ideas of the just reward for CEOs. However, the method used to estimate the just reward is an indirect method that utilizes the justice evaluation function. Accordingly, we provide a brief background not only on the just reward but also on the justice evaluation and their associated functions. Just Reward Function and the Principles of Microjustice. The just reward is the observer’s idea of the just reward for a particular rewardee. It can be expressed as a function of characteristics of the rewardee and the rewardee’s situation. This representation of the just reward function is owed to Berger, Zelditch, Anderson, and Cohen (1972), as shown in Jasso (1983), and is thus called the BZAC function. Of course, observers may disagree as to which worker/situational characteristics are relevant for just earnings or about the worth of such characteristics. Accordingly, we write a general just reward function: where C denotes the just reward and X denotes a vector of rewardee and situational 4 (2) characteristics. To illustrate, in the earnings realm, C represents just earnings, and the X vector contains both worker characteristics and situational characteristics, such as geographic region and industrial sector; some of the characteristics in the X vector may be salient to some observers and ignored by others. The parameters of the BZAC just reward function (e.g., intercept and slope coefficients) represent just rates of return – for example, just rate of return to schooling and just rate of return to experience, as well as a just gender multiplier, and so on. Following Brickman et al. (1981), these quantities, which guide determination of the just reward in the observer’s head, are collectively called the principles of microjustice. Just Reward Distribution and the Principles of Macrojustice. When an observer forms ideas about the just reward for a set of rewardees, these ideas are also guided by distributional considerations, and these considerations are visible in the distribution formed by the set of just rewards. Following Brickman et al. (1981), parameters of the observer-specific just reward distribution – such as its mean and inequality – are called the principles of macrojustice. Justice Evaluation Function. The justice evaluation is the observer’s assessment that a rewardee (self or other) is fairly or unfairly rewarded and, if unfairly rewarded, whether underrewarded or overrewarded, and to what degree. The justice evaluation, denoted J, arises from the comparison between an actual reward and a just reward. It is usually specified as the logarithm of the ratio of the actual reward, denoted A, to the just reward, denoted, as before, C (Jasso 1978, 1999, 2006): where denotes the signature constant. The sign of is called the framing coefficient, because it embodies the observer’s framing of the reward as a good or as a bad (negative for a bad, positive for a good); and the absolute value of is called the expressiveness coefficient, because it transforms the observer’s experience of justice into the expression thereof. The log-ratio form For fuller discussion of properties of the justice evaluation function, see Jasso (2007).3 In the behavioral model in (3), the justice evaluation function appears in its theoretical4 form, i.e., without an error term. Below it will be transformed into an empirically estimable form, including an error term. 5 (3) of the justice evaluation function has many appealing properties, and has been shown to be the only functional form which simultaneously satisfies two important conditions, scale invariance and additivity (Jasso 1990).3 Note that the justice evaluation serves to link the twin pillars of the justice literature: ideas of justice and reactions to injustice. Ideas of justice, as seen in equation (2), are one of the two arguments of the justice evaluation function; and reactions to injustice are the consequences of the justice evaluation. Thus, the justice evaluation connects the two foundational themes in the study of justice. Two-Equation Model. The method we use for estimating the just rewards is based on a design in which each observer judges the justice or injustice of the actual reward associated with each rewardee in a set of rewardees (Jasso and Rossi 1977; Jasso 1990, 2007). Thus, the underlying model is a two-equation model consisting of the justice evaluation function and the just reward function (here written for a single observer): where the justice evaluation, actual reward, just reward, and reward-relevant characteristics are denoted by lower-case letters, r indexes the rewardee, ð denotes the parameters of the just reward function, and is a classical error distributed independently with zero mean and constant variance (within the respondent-specific equation).4 As will be described in section 3.2, estimation of the observer-specific justice evaluation equation (the first equation in expression (3)), in which the just rewards are unobserved, yields an estimate of the signature constant , which is then used to calculate the true observer- 6 specific/rewardee-specific just reward . These estimated just rewards become the dependent variable in the observer-specific just reward equation (the second equation in expression (3)), which in turn yields estimates of the observer-specific principles of microjustice. Concomitantly, calculation of the mean and inequality measures in the observer-specific just reward distribution yields estimates of the observer-specific principles of macrojustice. 2.2. Justice of CEO Compensation People make justice judgments about a wide variety of rewardees, including self and others, the latter both known and unknown to them. It is a commonplace – and much expressed in private conversations, letters to the editor of newspapers and periodicals, radio talk shows, and, now, web logs – that this or that athlete is overpaid and this or that actor is underpaid, etc. CEOs are among the rewardees the justice of whose rewards is much evaluated. Several themes are discernible in public discussion of CEO compensation. First, the levels of CEO compensation are perceived as high; for example, the median CEO compensation in 2001 was $7.1 million, and the distribution is highly positively skewed (Söderström et al. 2003). Second, compensation differentials – say, between a nurse and a CEO – appear to many to be disproportionate. Third, CEO compensation increased dramatically in the last two decades of the twentieth century – for example, in the United States averaging 9% per year in the period 1980–1998 and outpacing not only compensation increases for rank and file workers but also the pay growth of 3.7% per year among the wealthiest Americans (Hall and Liebman 1998; Piketty and Saez 2006). Fourth, CEOs appear to have lost the trust of the general population; the prevailing image is that of a CEO negotiating large compensation packages while fraudulently and criminally misrepresenting corporate performance for personal gain (Meyer 2003). Fifth, the system of corporate governance, in particular the set of checks and balances, has become a focus of criticism. Of course, not all justice evaluations conclude with a verdict of overreward. For example, Crystal’s (2002) analysis of executive compensation in companies with 2001 revenue of $8 billion or more concluded that three of the CEOs are underpaid – including Warren Buffet Because the target CEOs in our study are newly hired as a CEO, we do not explicitly5 examine performance pay sensitivity, as is typical in the research literature (e.g., Murphy 1999). 7 of Berkshire Hathaway, whose business acumen is matched by his sense of ethics and fair play. The scholarly literature on the justice of CEO compensation is anchored by two pioneering data collection efforts – the International Social Survey Programme (ISSP) and the International Justice Research Project (ISJP) – which have obtained information concerning what respondents regard as the just pay for “chairman of a large national corporation” and “chairman of a large company,” respectively (Jasso 2007). However, these data do not lend themselves to estimating just pay for a broader range of CEOs – such as CEOs of small firms or multinational corporations. Moreover, they do not permit nuanced judgments that take into account personal characteristics of the CEO such as age or gender or other firm characteristics such as industry – that is, they do not permit estimation of just reward functions and the principles of microjustice. Accordingly, we use the factorial-survey justice design developed by Jasso and Rossi (1977) in order to achieve greater specificity. We specify a just compensation function that parallels the actual compensation functions discussed in the literature. The just compensation function includes characteristics of CEOs and of their firms which figure in both the actual compensation literature and in justice discussions, such characteristics as the age, gender, schooling, and experience of the CEO and the size and location of the firm (Baker and Hall 2004; Boxman et al. 1991; Conyon and Murphy 2000; Meyersson 1994; Murphy 1999; O’Reilly and O’Neill 2003; Rosen 1992). In the first application of the framework developed in this paper, we focus on CEOs newly hired as a CEO.5 2.3. MBA Students and the Justice of CEO Compensation MBA students occupy a crossroads in the justice and CEO landscape. Like their fellows from high school and in common with the broader population, they judge the justice of CEO compensation. But unlike the broader population, they may have aspirations to become a CEO or take on other positions within the corporate world. And they have taken a significant step in the direction of casting their lot with business. Discerning their ideas of justice about CEO 8 compensation provides a glimpse into the mindset of future entrepreneurs, CEOs, and board members. Note that to the extent that MBA students are drawn from around the world, they represent an international elite and thus their views may reflect both their national origins and their common global culture. 3. METHOD: FACTORIAL SURVEY ANALYSIS AND JUSTICE JUDGMENTS OF CEO COMPENSATION To learn what MBA students regard as just compensation for CEOs and to estimate the justice principles guiding their judgments, we use Rossi’s factorial survey method (Rossi 1979; Rossi and Anderson 1982; Rossi and Berk 1985; Jasso 2006), which has proved especially useful in studies of distributive justice, making it possible to obtain justice judgments about large sets of richly described fictitious rewardees (Berk and Rossi 1977; Jasso and Rossi 1977; Jasso 2007). The general factorial survey method provides several avenues for obtaining respondents’ ideas of the just reward, including a direct method and (two versions of) an indirect method (Jasso 2007). The research reported here used the one-reward-per-rewardee version of the indirect method, in which a hypothetical actual reward is randomly attached to each rewardee, and respondents assess the fairness or unfairness of the actual rewards. The indirect method yields estimates of the just reward that are uncontaminated by socialization, rhetorical, political-correctness, or other disclosure mechanisms. Briefly, we presented to respondents a set of 40 hypothetical CEOs, described in terms of own and firm characteristics, including a random compensation amount, and we asked the respondents to rate the justice or relative injustice of the hypothetical earnings. We used the obtained justice evaluations to estimate for each respondent the amount he or she thinks just for each of the hypothetical CEOs (the method involves a two-step procedure, described below). Next we used the estimated just compensation amounts to estimate for each respondent the principles of microjustice and macrojustice guiding his/her judgments. 9 3.1. Data Collection in the Factorial Survey Analysis of CEO Compensation The design of the data collection has three main ingredients: a sample of respondents, a population of hypothetical CEOs (the “vignettes”) from which random samples are drawn and randomly assigned to respondents, and a rating task. 3.1.1. Vignette Samples Vignette Characteristics. The vignettes include CEO and firm characteristics, plus a hypothetical amount of total direct compensation proposed for the CEO’s first year as CEO of this firm. Total direct compensation consists of base salary, bonus, restricted stock and long- term incentives -- everything except stock option grants. MBA students would be familiar with these components of executive compensation. Levels/values of vignette characteristics. Table 1 presents the vignette characteristics, together with their levels and values. As shown, age varies from 20 years to 70 years, schooling from completion of sixth grade to a doctoral degree, CEO compensation from fifty thousand to sixty million dollars. Of course, the real world is sufficiently diverse that most of the values in the vignettes have real-world counterparts. For example, in 2004, excluding those CEOs who at their request received total compensation of one dollar, CEO compensation in the top 500 U.S. companies ranged from $ 82,000 to $ 230,554,000 (www.forbes.com). – Table 1 about here – Firm headquarters is specified as being in one of three locations -- the United States, Europe, and Asia. The vignettes describe the CEO’s firm as being in one of four major industries – manufacturing, finance and insurance, information, and wholesale trade. Population of vignettes and drawing vignette samples. To obtain the random samples of vignettes to present to respondents, we followed these procedures: First, we fully crossed all characteristics except sex. The number of possible vignettes (Cartesian product) is: 11 × 15 × 16 × 3 × 4 × 27 × 27 = 23,094,720. Second, we eliminated logically impossible combinations, following the specifications given in the note to Table 1; for example, age and experience as a CEO could not yield a CEO who became a CEO before age 16. Third, we drew http://www.forbes.com). 10 two random samples, each of size 20 (called Decks 1 and 2). Fourth, each of the two random samples was used to generate two mirror-image samples with respect to sex, one describing men, the other women (e.g., Deck 1 gives rise to two decks, the all-female Deck 1a and the all-male Deck 1b). Finally, two superdecks of size 40 were constructed by taking the male version of one sample and the female version of the other sample, and vice-versa (e.g., Deck 1a and Deck 2b form one superdeck). Thus, each respondent received a pack with 40 vignettes. Though the 20 male and 20 female CEOs in each respondent’s pack are not mirror images of each other, across all respondents the male and female CEOs are indeed mirror images of each other. 3.1.2. Rating Task The respondent was asked to rate the justice or injustice of the hypothetical salary randomly attached to each CEO. The rating task used a number-matching technique developed by S. S. Stevens (1975), which gives respondents maximal freedom to map the subjective justice continuum onto numbers. The number zero is used to represent perfect justice, negative numbers to represent unjust underpayment, and positive numbers to represent unjust overpayment. The usual protocol for factorial survey studies was followed (Jasso 2006, 2007). The instructions were read aloud, examples provided, questions answered. The instructions, besides describing the justice evaluation rating task, highlight the randomness of the attached hypothetical actual earnings and, to activate the full real-number line, make explicit mention of fractions and decimals; as well, to preserve independence of the ratings, the instructions say that respondents may change any of their ratings. Facsimiles of the instructions and of a vignette appear in Jasso (2006:412, 415). The rating provided by the respondent for each rewardee is the justice evaluation described above (equation (2)) and produced by a comparison of the actual reward included in the vignette with the respondent’s own idea of the just reward for the particular rewardee. 3.1.3. Respondent Samples We selected two samples of MBA students, one from a Swedish institution, the other 11 (4) (5) (6) from a U.S. institution. The two institutions have similar curriculums, and the courses have similar content. Both institutions have a diverse student body drawing both from different domestic ethnicities and different origin countries. The proportion women is low to moderate in the two institutions, approximately 14% in the Swedish institution and 26% in the U.S. institution. In both institutions, we conducted the survey in the largest core course. 3.2. Estimating the Just CEO Compensation As noted, we use the one-reward-per-rewardee version of the indirect method to estimate the amount of compensation that each respondent regards as just for each fictitious CEO. The first step is to estimate the justice evaluation equation in the two-equation model (expression (3)), written, as before, for a single respondent: To begin, we transform the theoretical justice evaluation equation in (4), which has no error and in which the true just reward is unobserved, into an estimable empirical form, re-writing it as a simple regression equation with a stochastic term , where obeys the classical assumptions. Because the respondent’s ideas of the just reward for each fictitious rewardee are unobserved, they are absorbed into the regression intercept , which can be shown, by properties of linear regression, to amalgamate all the unobserved true just rewards: This means that great care must be exercised in the estimation of (5) to guard against omitted- variables bias, which would arise if there is a correlation between the actual rewards and the unobserved just rewards. The steps taken to guard against such error are, first, ensure that the correlation of the actual reward and the reward-relevant characteristics (the CEO and firm characteristics) is zero in the vignette population, and, second, make clear to the respondents that the actual reward is random, stating this explicitly (“Each CEO has been randomly assigned a hypothetical total compensation for the first year.”). 12 (7) Accordingly, estimation, for each respondent separately, of the empirical justice evaluation function in (5) yields an estimate of the signature constant , from which the framing and expressiveness coefficients are immediately obtained. Because in the factorial survey the descriptions of the rewardees are designed by the investigator and the actual reward is uncorrelated with the reward-relevant characteristics, the regressor is fixed in the statistical sense and uncorrelated with the error, and, hence, the estimate of the signature constant has the desirable properties of unbiasedness and consistency. To estimate the true just reward, we re-arrange the terms in the justice evaluation equation in expression (4), obtaining the formula for estimating the true just reward: where denotes the exponential function. Accordingly, when the justice evaluation equation is combined with the factorial survey design developed by Jasso and Rossi (1977), the factorial survey justice design provides the actual reward, the justice evaluation is obtained from the respondent, and the signature constant is estimated via statistical estimation of the equation (as shown above), leaving only one unknown – the just reward – which is easily solved for. The just rewards obtained by this method, being nonlinear transformations of an unbiased and consistent estimate -- of the signature constant -- lose unbiasedness but, by Slutsky's theorem, remain consistent. Thus, estimates obtained by the one-reward-per-rewardee version of the indirect method have the desirable properties that they are free of disclosure bias and that they are consistent but the undesirable property that they are biased. To mitigate bias and achieve the benefits of consistency, sample size is important. Though more research is needed to gauge optimal sample sizes, an initial rule is that vignettes number at least forty. 3.3. Estimating the Principles of Microjustice and Macrojustice: Just Reward Functions and Just Reward Distributions To estimate the respondent-specific just reward functions, we regress, separately for each respondent, the natural logarithm of just CEO compensation (estimated via formula (7)) on the CEO and firm characteristics. The obtained estimates, or transformations thereof, constitute The three models are labeled as in Johnston and DiNardo (1997:129-130).6 13 estimates of the respondent-specific principles of microjustice. To illustrate, the coefficient of schooling provides an estimate of the just earnings return to investment in an additional year of schooling. Age and experience are each represented by a quadratic form (i.e., by two regressors, such as age and age-squared), so that the just return to age or to experience is estimated by the two coefficients jointly. The exponential of the coefficient of the binary sex variable, measures the gender multiplier; women are coded “1" and thus the multiplier is applied to the earnings of females, so that subtracting one yields the tax (if negative) or bonus (if positive) on women's earnings, relative to the earnings of comparable men, in percentage points. The gender multiplier has a natural interpretation as the ratio of female to male earnings; a gender multiplier of .8 would indicate the view that the just earnings for a woman is 80% of the just earnings for a comparable man. To test homogeneity of the respondent-specific just reward equations, we estimate three models and perform three tests contrasting them. Model I specifies a pooled equation in which6 all respondents have the same intercept and the same slopes. Model II retains common slopes but allows each respondent to have a unique intercept. Model III is the set of respondent-specific equations in which each respondent has both a unique intercept and unique slopes. Test 1 contrasts Model I with Model II. Test 2 contrasts Model II with Model III. Test 3 contrasts Model I with Model III. The observer-specific just rewards form the just reward distribution. To estimate the principles of macrojustice, we calculate, for each respondent-specific distribution, the mean, median, and four measures of inequality. 4. RESULTS 4.1. Preliminaries Of the 47 respondents in the Swedish study, 45 provided numerical nonconstant ratings, Factorial survey justice studies since the earliest days have found evidence of7 “contrarian” individuals, e.g., persons who regard earnings as a bad or time in prison as a good – exemplifying the old adage that one person’s meat is another’s poison. Deleting contrarians removes one source of variability, producing more conservative homogeneity tests. 14 and of these, 43 provided information on gender (27 males and 16 females). Twenty-six of the 27 men and 13 of the 16 women rated all 40 vignettes; only 6 vignettes were left unrated, and the fewest number rated was 38. Estimation of the justice evaluation equations indicated that one male and one female each regarded earnings as a bad. These two respondents were dropped,7 leaving a usable Swedish sample of 26 males and 15 females. In the U.S. sample, all 36 respondents provided numerical nonconstant ratings as well as gender information (30 males and 6 females). However, there are too few female respondents to constitute a female sample. Moreover, one of the men rated fewer than 30 vignettes and was eliminated, leaving a usable U.S. male sample of size 29. Twenty-four of the 29 men rated all 40 vignettes; one each rated 31, 34, and 35 vignettes, and 2 rated 39 vignettes. Accordingly, the data to be analyzed include three subsamples and enable a contrast between male MBA students in Sweden and in the United States and a second contrast between male and female MBA students in Sweden. 4.2. Estimates of Just CEO Compensation Using the procedure described above, we estimated for each respondent the amount of compensation he/she thought just for each of the CEOs. The estimates are arrayed in a just reward matrix. To illustrate, Table 2 reports a portion of the just earnings matrix, showing the just earnings amounts for a quarter of the vignettes, namely ten each from two mirror-image decks. Our focus in this paper is on the rows of the matrix – namely, the respondent-specific just reward distributions to which we return in section 4.4 below. Of course, the rewardee-specific just reward distributions in the columns can also be usefully investigated – Table 2 about here -- 4.3. Principles of Microjustice We begin by estimating the respondent-specific just reward equations. For each 15 respondent, the forty logged just earnings amounts are regressed on the CEO and firm characteristics. Next, we carry out the homogeneity tests described in section 3.3, separately within each of the three samples. In all three samples, all three tests reject homogeneity at very high levels of statistical significance (beyond the .0001 level). We conclude that in forming their ideas of just compensation respondents differ in the weights they attach to CEO and firm characteristics. As a brief illustration, consider the results for the Swedish male sample (Table 3); corresponding tables for the other two samples are available from the authors. The value of R- squared in the Model I equation, which constrains all respondents to have the same intercept and the same slopes, is a meager .113. Model II, which allows respondents to have unique intercepts, attains a value of R-squared of .346, or triple that in Model I. Model III, which permits respondents to have their own intercepts and slopes, reaches an R-squared of .591, which almost doubles that in Model II and is over 5 times that in Model I. – Table 3 about here – Thus, the homogeneity tests yield the first important result: MBA students, even within country and within gender, do not agree with each other on the just bases for CEO compensation. As will be discussed, this may reflect the students’ international origins and/or their independence of mind. To assess the extent of agreements and disagreements, we examine the respondent- specific equation estimates. For each respondent, we have estimates of twelve coefficients, one intercept, and one value of R-squared. The thirteen parameter estimates satisfy the conditions for unbiasedness. We summarize the results in two ways. First, we present in panel A of Table 4 summary characteristics of all the coefficients plus R-squared. Second, we present graphs of the sample-specific quantile functions associated with several of the measures. The quantile function plots the value of a variable on its cumulative relative frequency, so that it is visually evident what proportion of respondents have values smaller than the plotted values. These plots permit immediate assessment of interrespondent disagreements and of similarity or dissimilarity Such a common Weltanschauung should not be too surprising, given that MBA8 students the world over have a similar curriculum. Moreover, asked about their major sources of business information, MBA students at both institutions mentioned the same three periodicals: The Wall Street Journal, The Financial Times, and The Economist. Further, both institutions draw students from all over the world. In the graph, the upper extreme values are interpolated for the Swedish women and the9 U.S. men. 16 of the distributions across the three samples. – Table 4 about here -- Before discussing the estimates of the respondent-specific just CEO compensation equations, we inspect their values of R-squared (panel A of Table 4 and Figure 1). As shown, the values of R-squared range from .142 to .726. The means and medians in all three samples hover between .44 and .49. These are substantial magnitudes, indicating that, although the respondents may disagree with each other on the importance associated with particular CEO and firm characteristics, they have coherent and orderly views concerning the effects of CEO and firm characteristics on just CEO compensation. As well, the values of R-squared indicate that the particular set of CEO and firm characteristics included in the vignettes are indeed relevant to the just pay for CEOs, in the respondents’ eyes. – Figure 1 about here – Figure 1 tells an additional story. Notice how close together the three sample-specific distributions lie. Although there is considerable variability within sample, the three samples are very similar. These results suggest a common Weltanschauung among MBA students in both the Swedish and the U.S. institutions.8 The effect of CEO gender on just compensation is represented by the gender multiplier (Table 4, panel B, and Figure 2, panel A). As shown, the medians are in the range .84-.94, indicating that the median respondent regards as just an amount for women that is 84% to 94% that of otherwise identical male CEOs. Again, the three distributions are very similar to each other, parting company only at the extremes, especially the upper extreme.9 – Figure 2 about here – The quintessential example of entrepreneurial college dropouts is Bill Gates, founder10 of Microsoft. Another well-known example is Michael Dell, founder of Dell Computer (Dell 2003). The plots omit a total of three values (from the graphs but not from the underlying11 distributions) – one each at the bottom and top in the Swedish male sample, and one at the top in the Swedish female sample. 17 The respondent-specific estimates for the just rate of return to schooling (Table 4, panels A and B, Figure 2, panel B) indicate not only the large individual differences already expected but also somewhat less similarity across the three samples, especially in the bottom half of the distributions. The median just rate of return to schooling is substantially higher among the Swedish men (9.5%) than among the Swedish women and U.S. men (5.5% and 5.3%, respectively). Swedish women also have the bottom third of the distribution with lower just returns than U.S. men. These results echo currents in the compensation literature, including the glory stories of entrepreneurial college dropouts, the view of schooling as a credentialing device, and the notion that schooling may be consumption as well as investment.10 The parabolas representing operation of experience as a CEO are concave downwards in a majority of each sample (65%, 73%, and 59%, respectively, among Swedish men, Swedish women, and U.S. men). For these subsets, we show the quantile function of the sample-specific distributions of the years of experience at which just compensation peaks (Figure 2, panel C). 11 Thus, these respondents judge as just a starting compensation for newly-hired CEOs that notices previous experience as a CEO but that peaks at a median experience of 6-9 years. The firm location variables give rise to six possible orderings. The two orderings in which the United States is thought to provide larger just compensation characterize a plurality of respondents in all three samples, although the two orderings in which Asia has the larger coefficient is a strong contender among the U.S. male sample. Among the two Swedish samples, the two orderings with Asia at the top characterize the fewest number of respondents. These results suggest that in forming ideas of just compensation for CEOs, our respondents take into account the location of the firm headquarters but they disagree concerning which locations make As suggested by inspection of the graphs and tabulated figures, there is one omitted12 value at the bottom of the range (among the U.S. men) and several at the top (one among Swedish men, three among Swedish women, and four among U.S. men). 18 high earnings more appropriate. The firm industry variables give rise to 24 possible orderings. All but one of the 24 possible orderings were used by at least one respondent. In each sample, the largest number of respondents associated with a single ordering are 4, 5, and 3 among Swedish men, Swedish women, and U.S. men, respectively. The estimates for the effect of firm capitalization on just CEO compensation (Table 4, panel A, and Figure 2, panel D) show the now familiar pattern associated with the effects of quantitative characteristics – variability across individuals, similarity across samples. The12 medians lie in the range .14-.26. Thus, on average, respondents regard as just a CEO compensation that increases by approximately .20% for a 1% increase in firm capitalization. In the vocabulary of economics, the estimated elasticity of CEO just compensation with respect to firm capitalization is in the range of .14 to .26 – a range consistent with Rosen’s (1992) estimated range of .20 to .30. Interestingly, the estimates in the two men’s samples are even more similar to Rosen’s estimates – a mean and median of the estimated elasticities of .23-.24 and .18-.26, respectively. 4.4. Principles of Macrojustice Table 4 reports in panel C summary characteristics for the median and for the four inequality measures calculated on the respondent-specific just reward distributions. Graphs of the sample-specific quantile functions associated with the median and with the inequality measures are presented in Figures 3 and 4. – Figures 3 and 4 about here – The plots for the medians of the respondent-specific just reward distributions (Figure 3) indicate interrespondent similarity over most of the region. Moreover, the three plots are very similar, indicating similarity across the three samples. This pattern differs from the pattern 19 observed in the principles of microjustice of within-sample variability combined with cross- sample similarity; here we observe similarity both within and across samples. The graphs of the inequality measures (Table 4), however, display the same pattern as the principles of microjustice – great variability across respondents, great similarity across samples. Substantively, respondents regard as fair very high levels of inequality in CEO compensation. Most of the minimums are quite high – for example, the smallest values of the Gini index among Swedish men and women are .46 and .50, respectively, values higher than in the broader U.S. income distribution. The means and medians are in the range of .76-.78. At the upper extremes of the distributions, the magnitudes approach unity, the theoretical upper limit of the Gini index. In the MLD, however, there is some dissimilarity across the three samples, albeit confined to the top half of the distribution. Swedish women appear tolerant of greater inequality (higher MLD). In sum, the levels of inequality in CEO compensation that respondents regard as just are quite high. 5. SUMMARY AND DISCUSSION In this paper we developed a framework for studying individuals’ ideas about what constitutes just compensation for chief executive officers (CEOs), and we reported the results of the first application of the framework, assessing MBA students’ ideas about just CEO pay, focusing on three samples: Swedish men, Swedish women, and U.S. men. Our main results are: First, we obtained estimates of each respondent’s ideas of the just pay for each of 40 fictitious CEOs, of each respondent’s just reward equation and the principles of microjustice, and of each respondent’s just reward distribution and the principles of macrojustice. These results make it possible to construct characterizations of respondents and CEOs, for example, that one respondent regards as just a return to schooling of 10 percent and another a return to schooling of 20 percent, that one respondent regards as just a Gini of .5 and another a Gini of .982, and so on. Second, within each of the three samples, there is substantial 20 inter-individual variation in the principles of microjustice; that is, in forming ideas of just CEO pay, people differ in the weights they place on CEO and firm characteristics. Third, there is remarkable similarity in the distributions of the principles of microjustice across the three samples. Fourth, within each sample, there is broad agreement on the median just CEO compensation but substantial inter-individual variation in the inequality subset of the principles of macrojustice; that is, people differ in their tolerance for inequality. Fifth, there is remarkable similarity in the distributions of the principles of macrojustice across the three samples. The estimates of the principles of justice provide an array of useful and suggestive results. For example, the distributions of observer-specific elasticity of just CEO compensation with respect to firm capitalization have medians in the range of .14-.26 – similar to the range of .20-.35 found by Rosen (1992). Further, the median respondents regard as just an amount of pay for women CEOs that is 84% to 94% that of otherwise identical male CEOs. With respect to variability in just CEO compensation, estimates of the principles of macrojustice indicate that the MBA students regard as just rather high levels of inequality in CEO compensation (e.g., median Gini index values of .76-.78), possibly dulling the senses to economic inequality in the larger population, where a Gini of .50 would be considered too high by most observers. The findings of substantial inter-respondent differences on the principles of justice and of remarkable similarity in the distributions of principles of justice across the three samples jointly provide evidence for the existence of a global business culture, but one which, consistent with ideals of risk, innovation, and individualism, and possibly diverse origins, accommodates wide individual differences. Of course, the similarity we found between MBA students in Sweden and the United States may not extend to the general populations of the two countries. It is important to monitor views of CEO pay both inside and outside the business world, for a global business culture at odds with the general population would be a source of political tension both within and between national cultures. The findings on the effects of CEO gender on ideas of just pay suggest substantial gender attentiveness on the part of MBA students. The factorial survey method makes it possible to 21 retrieve ideas of fairness that respondents might otherwise be reluctant to express. Whether gender attentiveness among MBA students persists, increases, or diminishes is a question for future research. Recent studies carried out in college samples in the United States (e.g., Jasso and Webster 1999) indicate that gender attentiveness is shifting. While U.S. college students increasingly assign equal just pay to otherwise identical male and female workers, they are not completely blind to gender, for the mechanisms by which they generate ideas of just earnings remain gender-attentive (for example, noticing gender in assigning just base pay or just returns to schooling). It will be important to monitor such shifts among MBA students. The factorial survey design is uniquely suited for this purpose. There are several important directions for future research. We highlight three. Methodologically, an important task is to systematically contrast direct and indirect methods for measuring just pay, in order to understand the precise nature of the differences between them, to calibrate results across studies, and to help in research design. A second methodological task, building on Jasso (2006:4003-4007), is to examine sensitivity of indirect methods to alternate specifications of the justice evaluation function, assessing, for example, families of functions that share major properties with the logarithmic-ratio function. Substantively, an important question for future research is to document ideas of just CEO pay among the general population as well as among other special target samples, such as workers, union members, regulators, legislators, business school faculty, faculty and students in other disciplines, and CEOs themselves, doing so not only in Sweden and the United States but also in additional countries around the world and repeating such studies periodically. Whether the world as a whole is becoming more similar in its views, whether, alternatively, pockets of the world’s population are becoming internally more similar but polarized vis-a-vis each other – these are vital questions for social, economic, and political development and for the well-being of the world’s people. 22 REFERENCES Arts, Wil, Piet Hermkens, and Peter van Wijck. 1991. “Income and the Idea of Justice: Principles, Judgments, and Their Framing.” Journal of Economic Psychology 12:121- 140. Atkinson, Anthony B., and Thomas Piketty. 2006. Top Incomes Over the Twentieth Century. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Baker, George P., and Brian J. Hall. 2004. “CEO Incentives and Firm Size.” Journal of Labor Economics 22:767-798 Berger, Joseph, Morris Zelditch, Bo Anderson, and Bernard P. Cohen. 1972. "Structural Aspects of Distributive Justice: A Status-Value Formulation." Pp. 119-246 in Joseph Berger, Morris Zelditch, and Bo Anderson (eds.), Sociological Theories in Progress, Volume 2. Boston: Houghton Mifflin. Berk, Richard A., and Peter H. Rossi. 1977. Prison Reform and State Elites . Cambridge, MA: Ballinger. Bok, Derek. 1993. The Cost of Talent: How Executives and Professionals Are Paid and How It Affects America. New York: Free Press. Boxman, Ed A. W., Paul M. De Graaf, and Hendrik D. Flap. 1991. “The Impact of Social and Human Capital on the Income Attainment of Dutch Managers.” Social Networks 13:51- 73. Brickman, Philip, R. Folger, E. Goode, and Y. Schul. 1981. “Micro and Macro Justice.” Pp. 173-202 in M. J. Lerner and S. C. Lerner (eds.), The Justice Motive in Social Behavior. New York: Plenum. Conyon, Martin, and Kevin Murphy. 2000. “The Prince and the Pauper? CEO Pay in the United States and the United Kingdom.” The Economic Journal 110:640-671. Crystal, Graef. 2002. “No Accounting for CEO Pay Gap.” www.bloomberg.com . Dell, Michael S. (with Patricia R. Olsen). 2003. “More Fun Than School.” The New York Times, Business Section, 9 March 2003. http://www.bloomberg.com 23 Hall, Brian J., and Jeffrey B. Liebman. 1998. “Are CEOs Really Paid Like Bureaucrats?” Quarterly Journal of Economics 113:653-691. Jasso, Guillermina. 1978. "On the Justice of Earnings: A New Specification of the Justice Evaluation Function." American Journal of Sociology 83:1398-1419. ______. 1983. "Fairness of Individual Rewards and Fairness of the Reward Distribution: Specifying the Inconsistency between the Micro and Macro Principles of Justice." Social Psychology Quarterly 46:185-199. ______. 1988. "Whom Shall We Welcome? Elite Judgments of the Criteria for the Selection of Immigrants." American Sociological Review 53:919-932. ______. 1990. "Methods for the Theoretical and Empirical Analysis of Comparison Processes." Sociological Methodology 20:369-419. ______. 2006. “Factorial Survey Methods for Studying Beliefs and Judgments.” Sociological Methods and Research 34:334-423. ______. 2007. “Studying Justice: Measurement, Estimation, and Analysis of the Actual Reward and the Just Reward.” Pp. 225-253 in Kjell Törnblom and Riel Vermunt (eds.), Distributive and Procedural Justice: Research and Social Applications. London, UK: Ashgate. Manuscript available as IZA Discussion Paper No. 2592 at www.iza.org. ______, and Peter H. Rossi. 1977. "Distributive Justice and Earned Income." American Sociological Review 42:639-651. ______, and Murray Webster, Jr. 1999. "Assessing the Gender Gap in Just Earnings and Its Underlying Mechanisms." Social Psychology Quarterly 62:367-380. ______, and Bernd Wegener. 1997. "Methods for Empirical Justice Analysis: Part I. Framework, Models, and Quantities." Social Justice Research 10:393-430. Johnston, Jack, and John DiNardo. 1997. Econometric Methods. Fourth edition. New York, NY: McGraw-Hill. Kelley, Jonathan, and M. D. R. Evans. 1993. “The Legitimation of Inequality: Occupational Earnings in Nine Countries.” American Journal of Sociology 99:75-125. http://www.iza.org. 24 Master, Melissa. 2002. “How Much Should A CEO Make?” Across the Board (November/December). Website of The Conference Board (www.conference-board.org ). McGeehan, Patrick. 2003. “Executive Pay: A Special Report.” The New York Times, 6 April 2003. Meyer, Pearl. 2003. “From Halos to Horns: Demonizing the American CEO.” Paper available at www.execpay.com . Meyersson, Eva M. 1994. Kompensations Kontrakt I Börsnoterade Företag. Stockholm, Sweden: Almqvist & Wiksell International. Murphy, Kevin J. 1999. “Executive Compensation.” Handbook of Labor Economics 3B:2485- 2562. O’Reilly III, Charles A., and Olivia A. O’Neill. 2003. “Women’s Careers: The Impact of Sex and Gender Identity on Career Attainment.” Unpublished paper. Piketty, Thomas, and Emmanuel Saez. 2006. “The Evolution of Top Incomes: A Historical and International Perspective.” American Economic Review 96:200-205. Roine, Jesper, and Daniel Waldenström. 2006. “The Evolution of Top Incomes in an Egalitarian Society: Sweden 1903-2004.” IFN Working Paper Number 667. Rosen, Sherwin. 1992. “Contracts and the Market for Executives.” Pp. 181-211 in Lars Wein and Hans Wijkander (eds.), Contract Economics. Cambridge, MA, and Oxford, UK: Blackwell. Rossi, Peter H. 1979. "Vignette Analysis: Uncovering the Normative Structure of Complex Judgments." Pp. 176-186 in Qualitative and Quantitative Social Research: Papers in Honor of Paul F. Lazarsfeld, edited by Robert K. Merton, James S. Coleman, and Peter H. Rossi. New York: Free Press. _____, and Andy B. Anderson. 1982. "The Factorial Survey Approach: an Introduction." Pp. 15-67 in Measuring Social Judgments: the Factorial Survey Approach, edited by Peter H. Rossi and Steven L. Nock. Beverly Hills: Sage. http://www.conference-board.org http://www.execpay.com 25 Söderström, Hans Tson, Erik Berglöf, Bengt Holmström, Peter Högfeldt, and Eva M. Meyersson Milgrom. 2003. Corporate Governance and Structural Change: European Challenges. Stockholm, Sweden: SNS Förlag. Stevens, S. S. 1975. Psychophysics: an Introduction to Its Perceptual, Neural, and Social Prospects. Edited by Geraldine Stevens. New York: Wiley. Svallfors, Stefan. 1997. “Worlds of Welfare and Attitudes to Redistribution: A Comparison of Eight Western Nations.” European Sociological Review 13:283-304. Verwiebe, Roland, and Bernd Wegener. 2000. “Social Inequality and the Perceived Income Justice Gap.” Social Justice Research 13:123-149. Wall Street Journal. 2003. “Special Report: Executive Pay.” April 14, 2003. Walster, Elaine, Ellen Berscheid, and G. William Walster. 1976. “New Directions in Equity Research.” Pp. 1-42 in Leonard Berkowitz and Elaine Walster (eds.), Equity Theory: Toward a General Theory of Social Interaction. New York: Academic. Wegener, Bernd. 1991. “Relative Deprivation and Social Mobility: Structural Constraints on Distributive Justice Judgements.” European Sociological Review 7:3-18. Table 1. Characteristics of the Fictitious CEOs Described in the Vignettes 1. Age Eleven levels, in increments of five years, from 20 to 70 years. 2. Sex (1) Male (2) Female 3. Years of Schooling Completed Fifteen levels, in increments of one year, from completion of sixth grade to a doctoral degree. 4. Years as CEO Sixteen levels, in increments of one year, from 0 to 15 years. 5. Firm Headquarters (1) United States (2) Europe (3) Asia 6. Industry of This Firm (1) Manufacturing (2) Finance and insurance (3) Information (4) Wholesale trade 7. Size of Firm – Capitalization Twenty-seven levels, from $50 million to $600 billion. [50m, 75m, 100m, 125m, 150m, 175m, 200m, 250m, 500m, 600m, 700m, 800m, 900m, 1b, 5b, 10b, 15b, 20b, 25b, 50b, 75b, 100b, 200b, 300b, 400b, 500b, 600b] 8. CEO Total Compensation (salary, signing bonus, value of restricted stock, savings and thrift plans, and other benefits, but excluding options) Twenty-seven levels, from $50 thousand to $600 million. [50t, 75t, 100t, 125t, 150t, 175t, 200t, 250t, 500t, 600t, 700t, 800t, 900t, 1m, 5m, 10m, 15m, 20m, 25m, 50m, 75m, 100m, 200m, 300m, 400m, 500m, 600m] Note: The population of fictitious CEOs (called "vignettes") consists of all the logically possible combinations of characteristics. Logically impossible combinations are deleted. These are defined as meeting one of the following conditions: (i) age minus schooling LT 5; (ii) age minus years as CEO LT 16; and (iii) capitalization/compensation LT 10. Random samples are drawn from the adjusted population for presentation to respondents. Table 2. Estimated CEO Just Earnings Matrix: Just Earnings (in Thousands of 2001$) for CEOs, as Judged by MBA Students, Sweden 2001 ----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- Resp | CEO ID, Deck 1a ID | 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 ----------+------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------ 1 | 1000 151523 18142 151523 175 11010 1783 19756 2469 390 2 | 701 295 2349 63 222 1179 839 8516 1064 1863 5 | 134 2785 449 1246 175 999 160 629 223 175 7 | 104 2177 13 106 175 200 376 376 962 372 9 | 537 1378 551 2567 401 5513 1211 11841 2241 3921 11 | 2643 69 1872 483 175 731 800 103202 100 463 15 | 1000 193 25 141 350 951 800 1599 283 350 17 | 455 27385 120941 1170 36 22643 8512 199209 484 95846 19 | 323 155 273 478 175 619 800 7652 956 541 21 | 1000 3312 2277 549 175 13249 15992 8785 331 1056 23 | 104 123 273 1182 175 776 638 12037 22639 275 25 | 1000 90335 256 115 154 1606 985 1213 230 216 27 | 9344 4365 2676 4365 1635 17461 18273 18273 8730 6250 29 | 1000 234 2476 11018 3819 432 171 37736 22036 1767 32 | 1000 75 16724 75 175 299 1196 44569 5571 1306 34 | 1000 2697 9 2697 579 2189 5876 43154 149 389 37 | 414 292 734 1703 504 1167 1620 9456 203 354 39 | 10579 1359 574 1359 175 2116 800 34851 11192 175 40 | 6 279 144 89 56 200 254 1419 3117 56 42 | 3003 144 297 1665 471 1359 289 505 43 | 7 994 171 135 39 200 295 295 100 175 ----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- Resp | CEO ID, Deck 1b ID | 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 ----------+------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------ 3 | 202 30275 2263 248 35 992 800 5922 100 390 4 | 44 3174 140 398 175 2677 6374 143339 1339 830 10 | 1589 905 35389 529433 40516 418334 2.82e+10 12899 1.43e+27 557 12 | 312 1646 237 16905 1128 2054 250 8217 100 1797 14 | 149 335 215 129 16 77 18 309 100 175 16 | 261 191 48 50 146 200 511 800 100 274 18 | 290 24313 7254 93 8 20710 431 1485 470 3859 20 | 558 925 13949 925 98 11881 1434 1434 1849 1008 22 | 62147 18239 7683 18239 1027 3820 800 8470 36478 1853 24 | .102 50 25000 50 175 200 800 800 100 175 26 | 42969 1 163877 1 1 1311 800 225332 184634 7520 28 | 3 1382 395 174 76 303 152 800 100 76 30 | 270 356 3508 2539 337 200 800 1539 2639 648 31 | 1000 1712 730 50 5993 6849 800 800 17 1024 33 | 4 777 310 259 175 48278 800 193111 1554 175 35 | 782 134 622 317 210 370 432 2740 2171 175 36 | 1000 33665 37 353 336 134660 800 538639 175 38 | 400 230 257 575 175 5743 800 77879 2116 322 44 | 62 803 97 803 175 9749 800 206264 1606 2810 45 | 2 50 2178 1944 95 200 70 236 100 593 ----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------- Notes: Each respondent rated two twenty-vignette decks, either Deck 1a and Deck 2b or Deck 1b and Deck 2a. The ten CEOs shown are from Decks 1a and 1b (see text). CEOs with the same ID number are identical across these decks except for sex; the CEOs in Deck 1a are women and those in Deck 1b are men. Table 3. Summary of Estimated CEO Just Earnings Functions and Hypothesis Tests: Male MBA Students, Sweden 2001, 26 Respondents and 1039 Ratings Model/Test F-ratio (df) Model I: Common intercept and common slopes (13 parameters) 0.113 10.85 (12, 1026) Model II: Differential intercepts and common slopes (38 parameters) 0.346 14.32 (37, 1001) Model III: Differential intercepts and differential slopes (338 parameters) 0.591 3.00 (337, 701) Test of differential intercepts, conditional on common slopes: Model I vs. Model II 14.30 (25, 1001) Test of differential slopes, conditional on differential intercepts: Model II vs. Model III 1.40 (300, 701) Test of differential just earnings functions: Model I vs. Model III 2.52 (325, 701) Table 4. Summary Characteristics of Respondents’ Model III Equations and Selected Principles of Microjustice and Macrojustice: MBA Students, Sweden (2001) and the United States (2002) Swedish Men Swedish Women U.S. Men Mean S.D. Median Mean S.D. Median Mean S.D. Median A. Respondents’ Model III Equations Gender (1 = female) -.128 .806 -.0642 .0256 1.55 -.119 -.0249 1.39 -.180 Age .157 .177 .167 .0285 .602 .190 .209 .266 .149 Age-squared -.00154 .00175 -.00172 -.000372 .00564 -.00200 -.00208 .00271 -.00139 Years of schooling .0777 .0745 .0947 .0354 .118 .0549 .0528 .0878 .0528 Years as CEO .145 .234 .173 .426 .689 .271 .0355 .518 .0835 Years as CEO - squared -.00628 .0166 -.00737 -.0224 .0478 -.0132 -.00154 .0338 -.00559 Firm in Europe -.151 .740 -.134 -.416 .602 -.539 -.0547 .661 -.0668 Firm in Asia -.37 .839 -.220 -.428 1.18 -.519 .0179 1.15 -.0470 Firm in finance/insurance .119 .690 .0190 .869 .917 .998 -.146 1.34 -.0132 Firm in information -.00650 1.005 .0130 .640 1.16 .682 .235 .777 .174 Firm in wholesale trade -.182 .804 -.228 .665 1.70 -.00462 .251 1.02 .0534 Firm capitalization (log mil) .229 .203 .263 .382 .738 .138 .239 .280 .182 Constant -.856 4.45 -.749 .175 11.8 1.12 -1.34 6.57 .414 , just reward equation .491 .139 .466 .481 .140 .476 .440 .135 .436 B. Principles of Microjustice Just rate of return to school. .0777 .0745 .0947 .0354 .118 .0549 .0528 .0878 .0528 Just male base wage (2001K$) 27.0 60.6 .478 3.05 70.5 298.0 1.51 Just gender multiplier 1.15 .82 .938 9.01 31.3 .888 2.69 6.56 .835 C. Principles of Macrojustice Just median CEO pay (2 0 0 1 K $ ) 1270.39 1891.8 959.503 22871.2 83600.2 715.026 1738.23 2921.5 858.862 Just Gini’s ratio .735 .175 .757 .776 .171 .783 .783 .173 .764 Just Theil’s ratio 1.42 1.02 1.13 1.61 1.06 1.31 1.68 1.03 1.23 Just Atkinson’s ratio .68 .229 .727 .753 .209 .744 .761 .220 .778 Just MLD 1.86 1.92 1.30 4.95 10.6 1.36 3.22 4.74 1.51 Figure 2. Respondent-Specific Principles of Microjustice Figure 4. Respondent-Specific Principles of Macrojustice: Just Inequality ceo-text-2007-12-01-IZA.pdf ceo-tabs&figs-2007-12-13-port.pdf work_6su655zcibcbppdkdqyrhrxtxi ---- Resilience and Environmental Justice: Potential Linkages Procedia Economics and Finance 18 ( 2014 ) 416 – 424 2212-5671 © 2014 The Authors. Published by Elsevier B.V. This is an open access article under the CC BY-NC-ND license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/). Selection and/or peer-reviewed under responsibility of the Centre for Disaster Resilience, School of the Built Environment, University of Salford. doi: 10.1016/S2212-5671(14)00958-7 ScienceDirect Available online at www.sciencedirect.com 4th International Conference on Building Resilience, Building Resilience 2014, 8-10 September 2014, Salford Quays, United kingdom Resilience and Environmental Justice: Potential linkages Vicente Sandovala,c*, Claudia Gonzalez-Muzziob, Cristian Albornozc aThe Bartlett Development Planning Unit, University College London, WC1H 9EZ London, United Kingdom bAmbito Consultores Ltda., Santiago, Chile cResearch Center on Vulnerability and Disasters (CIVDES), University of Chile, Santiago, Chile. Abstract In May 2008, the remote city of Chaiten in Chile was evacuated due to the risk of a volcano eruption. Few days later, severe floods drove to the destruction of the almost entire city. In the months following the disaster, the Government developed projects that failed to relocate the city to a safer location as well as strategies to support the affected population aimed to improve community resilience. Contradictory institutional policies as well as the unforeseen effects of implemented bond schemes have resulted in a highly segregated and environmentally unjust city where public policiesʼ outputs are unevenly distributed. Thus, this paper addresses how some related processes of increasing resilience may impact negatively upon environmental justice, hence exploring a potential inverse relationship between resilience and environmental justice. Five years on, nearly half of the population have returned to Chaiten despite the refusal of the authorities. While northern Chaiten concentrates most of the population and investment, 160 families living in the southern Chaiten bear the lack of potable water and other basic services, and are more vulnerable to future disaster impacts. Split in two due to both geography and policies, Chaiten faces now two realities. © 2014 The Authors. Published by Elsevier B.V. Selection and/or peer-reviewed under responsibility of the Huddersfield Centre for Disaster Resilience, University of Huddersfield. Keywords: Community resilience; Environmental justice; Post-disaster policies; Vulnerability; Chaiten * Corresponding author. Tel.: +44 (20) 7679 1111; fax: +44 (0)20 679 1112. E-mail address: vicente.sandoval.11@ucl.ac.uk © 2014 The Authors. Published by Elsevier B.V. This is an open access article under the CC BY-NC-ND license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/). Selection and/or peer-reviewed under responsibility of the Centre for Disaster Resilience, School of the Built Environment, University of Salford. http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1016/S2212-5671(14)00958-7&domain=pdf 417 Vicente Sandoval et al. / Procedia Economics and Finance 18 ( 2014 ) 416 – 424 1. Introduction This paper covers the collaborative work of consulting projects, previous studies and observations conducted by authors from 2011. Likewise, it compasses several community focus groups, interviews to authorities and local leaders undertaken between March and July 2013. Besides, an extensive archival and literature review led the observation and analysis processes. This paper focuses on discussing the case of Chaiten and the potential linkages on the co-production of resilience and environmental justice. On the one hand, environmental justice is understood here as the uneven distribution of risks, but also to access to goods and services such as clean water, energy, healthcare and education as well as an appropriate urban environment, including green-spaces (Walker and Bulkeley, 2006). On the other hand, resilience is understood here as follows: “[T]he ability of a social system to respond and recover from disasters and include those inherent conditions that allow the system to absorb impacts and cope with an event, as well as post-event, adaptive processes that facilitate the ability of the social system to re-organize, change, and learn in response to a threat” (Cutter et al., 2008). Based on the case of Chaiten, the discussion is centered on how did the social system – i.e. community and authorities at different levels– react to disaster and cope with disaster effects; how did the different stakeholders organize, adapt and learn from the event and whether or not community is better prepared for future events. In terms of the relationship between resilience and environmental justice, it is argued that post-disaster actions taken by both the authorities and community aimed to increase resilience may have negatively impacted on environmental justice. Hence, this paper explores a potential inverse relationship between resilience and environmental justice (Schilderman and Lyons, 2010). Likewise, this paper argues that erratic policies have led to uneven distribution of risks and limited access to basic needs and services among the population of Chaiten. Finally, this paper illustrates how inequities that did not exist before Chaiten volcano have erupted. Accordingly, it asserts that Chaiten population or Chaiteninos are nowadays more vulnerable to disasters than before 2008. 2. Chaiten post-disaster context In May 2008, the Chaiten volcano, located in Los Lagos Region at southern Chile, erupted and caused the evacuation of Chaitenʼs entire population (De la Barrera et al., 2011) and some other localities of Palena Province– (around 8,000 inhabitants). The population was evacuated mainly to surrounding cities such as Puerto Montt and Castro, all located more than 100 km away by sea. Several days after the evacuation, lahars combined with rain caused a massive flood that left Chaiten devastated and uninhabitable (Lara, 2009). The city split in two due to the Blanco River changed its course creating a new riverbed and river mouth (see Figure 1). Economic losses were estimated in US$12 millions for insured public buildings only (Lara, 2009), and still there is no estimation of the total cost of the disaster. About US$129 millions were spent during the first year and more than US$3 million were used to rebuild public infrastructure (Presidencia de la Republica 2009). The disaster not only affected Chaiten, the capital of the Province of Palena, but also the entire province –18,971 inhabitants (INE 2002)–. Provincial Government had to move temporarily to Futaleufú city –another city in the Province–. Likewise, the Municipality of Chaiten governed virtually from Puerto Montt until 2011 when the provincial and municipal governments were reinstalled in Chaiten. Three reports commissioned by the Chilean Government (Moreno and Lara, 2008, Moreno et al., 2008, SERNAGEOMIN, 2009) designated Chaiten as highly prone to new eruptions and seismic activity. Accordingly, in February 2009, the Ministry of the Interior announced by media that “Unfortunately, Chaiten is dead” (La Nación, 2009). This announcement implied that neither reconstruction of Chaiten nor further investment of any kind would take place in the current location. Consequently, alternative plans based on the displacement of Chaiten to safer areas were considered. By end-2009, Santa Barbara was chosen as location of the New Chaiten. A Master Plan was developed by the Ministry of Housing and Urbanism (MINVU) and the first planned city in Chile during the 21st century would be built in three stages, the first one to be completed by end-2012 (MINVU 2010). 418 Vicente Sandoval et al. / Procedia Economics and Finance 18 ( 2014 ) 416 – 424 Fig. 1. Map of Chaiten and the Blanco River pre- and post-2008 river course (Based on INFRACON S.A., 2012). However, in February the same year, a massive earthquake struck the southern-central area of Chile killing around 500 people, affecting other two million, and causing around US$30 billions in losses (EM-DAT, 2013). Therefore, plans for the New Chaiten were not a priority anymore (Ramirez, 2010). Despite the political shift from a left-wing government to a right-wing government in 2010, President Pinera stated that Chaiten should be relocated confirming the decision of the prior administration. Contradictorily, by end- 2010, the northern sector of Chaiten was declared inhabitable again. This drastic change, the Government stated, was based on a technical study (Municipalidad de Chaitén, 2011) but it was also as response to the demand of more than 500 people who had informally returned to the city and resisted any attempt of eviction and relocation (Rojas, 2013). According to local people: “It was a tremendous struggle against Governmentʼs intentions for relocating us definitively [...] We stayed firm and strong because Chaiten has always been our land, we did not want to live anywhere else” (anonymous local leader, 2013, personal communication). Chaiten was then divided not only by the new course of the Blanco River but also, and more importantly, by a political status that only considered livable the northern sector of Chaiten. However, according to local authorities, by 2013 more than 160 families informally inhabited the southern sector. Those families still live in a precarious situation; lack of access to basic services such as potable water, electricity or sewage as well as to health, social care and education. Although there are not official records on the total population of Chaiten, authorities assert that by 2013 around 2500 people inhabited the city, including those in the southern sector. 3. Promoting resilience from the State: Setting the unequal distribution of risk and urban services Although Chaiten is located near several active volcanoes, people were no aware of volcanic hazards (INFRACON S.A., 2012). When the eruption occurred, there was no evacuation plan. However, in 24 hours 4,101 people were evacuated by sea –by both Navy and private ships–, and in few days, more than 8,000 people were forced to evacuate the area (Presidencia de la Republica 2009). On 2nd May 2008, the area was declared as “Catastrophe Zone” (Gobierno Regional de Los Lagos - GORE, 2008). This measure had one-year application extensible for the same period. In Chaiten, it was in force until May 2010. During that period, several resources were allocated to support the displaced population by a total of US$ 78,5 million (Presidencia de la Republica 2009). Emblematic measures included monthly bonds –up to US$1,000 per family– for more than 3,200 families during the first year and about 1,800 families the second year; compensation 419 Vicente Sandoval et al. / Procedia Economics and Finance 18 ( 2014 ) 416 – 424 bonds for farmers; grants for children education; housing subsidies of around US$ 20,000 for 2,235 families; subsidies to entrepreneurship and psychological support; among others (Gobierno Regional de Los Lagos - GORE, 2009, Gobierno Regional de Los Lagos - GORE, 2010, Presidencia de la Republica 2009). In addition, the special Act so-called “Chaiten Law” allowed the State to purchase properties paying for them their market price prior the eruption. Once approved, the State bought 889 properties for a total of US$30 million (El Mercurio, 2013), that represented more than 75% of the housing stock. About 70 housing units were rented by inhabitants in the northern sector. Others, who did not sell their properties, re-occupied their own houses. About 50 properties were assigned to Public offices to function and, nowadays, the State is offering to sell back 112 properties, mainly to their previous owners (El Mercurio, 2013). However, in the southern sector there is no permission to rent or buy back properties, thus the occupied houses are illegally inhabited (Rojas, 2013). Besides supporting the displaced population, the Government commissioned technical studies to assess the feasibility of rebuilding or relocating Chaiten. The conclusion was to relocate Chaiten to the near town of Santa Barbara, located 10 km north from Chaiten (Pontificia Universidad Católica de Chile PUC et al., 2009). The Master Plan for the New Chaiten (MINVU 2010) had an implementation cost evaluated in US$300 million (Silva, 2010). Although some public infrastructure was built in Santa Barbara for aeronautical services, police and other Public offices, no other action was implemented. By May 2010, the regional authorities decided to discard the New Chaiten because of its cost and the refusal of local population (Municipalidad de Chaitén, 2011). As evidence of lack of coordination, days after that announcement, President Pinera amended the regional intendant’s declaration and insisted that the New Chaiten would be built (El Mercurio en Internet, 2010). Ironically, in December 2010 the northern sector of Chaiten was definitively declared inhabitable (Municipalidad de Chaitén, 2011). In order to take the decision of inhabit Chaiten again, the Government commissioned another study, which concluded that local population could live near volcanic ash because its effects could be mitigated by cleaning and planting the area (CIMM T&S Consultores, 2010). In addition, the volcanic activity was decreasing and some areas were not at risk from new floods and lahars (Intendencia Región de Los Lagos, 2010) (see Figure 2). Thus, by declaring Chaiten inhabitable, the relocation project was aborted and hence the responsibility of deciding to live in a place at risk was transferred to local people. The Government valued the insistence of Chaiteninos to live in Chaiten: Fig. 2. Analysis of exposed areas and their categorization (Based on CIMM T&S Consultores, 2010, Municipalidad de Chaitén, 2011) 420 Vicente Sandoval et al. / Procedia Economics and Finance 18 ( 2014 ) 416 – 424 “The Government has the conviction that cities have to born and grow by normal evolutionary processes, supported by the local population and not under the desire and majoritarian support of the State [...]. Santa Barbara would be today a venture financed and directed exclusively by the State, without evidence of support from a substantial group of local population to accompany such entrepreneurship of relocation. Moreover, the present inhabitants of Chaiten, in an firm and courageous attitude, have assumed based on their freedom and responsibility, the decision of inhabiting their land and stay in there, which this Government values and recognizes as the spirit that must animate the decisions of territorial settling in the region.” (Intendencia Región de Los Lagos, 2010). By examining the State responses, this paper discusses that, although these responses aimed to promote resilience and lower levels of risk, actions taken have been the main cause of exacerbating vulnerability and triggering unequal distributions of risk, resilience, and environmental and social justice. 4. Community responses, reacting to the State Erratic communication about the causes of seismic activity in the area preceding the eruption and potential risks to the population can be exemplified in a meeting between representatives of Chaiten population and the Regional Government few days before the eruption; “[T]he situation about tremors was so unclear and confuse that the conversation turned to the effects of drought in the region” (anonymous local leader, 2013, personal communication). Despite this, most of the population accepted the evacuation –without resistance– immediately when the authorities decided it. Both authorities and people considered the evacuation of the city as an appropriate preventive measure when pondering the risk of eruption. However, evacuees were guided with no predefined order to disperse cities in the region. In some cases, families were parted because women and children were evacuated first. Furthermore, the existing social organization was disarticulated and no interlocutors were able to represent the dispersed population or establish communication with regional and local authorities (Mardones et al., 2011). To face uncertainty, Chaiteninos configured a collective force named “Children and friends of Chaiten” in order to communicate to authorities their needs as well as their intention to return to the city. Due to the low impact they had on media, some of them decided to occupy Chaiten despite the existing ban. Some media agencies named them “The Rebels” (Rojas, 2013). Living in the abandoned city meant they had to manage to get potable water from a little stream they connected to water pipes, while energy was obtained from a diesel generator. People organized themselves to clean the streets and to repair their houses. They also redefined their previous livelihoods into subsistence strategies to face the scarcity of goods and products available in the city, with no commerce or jobs available. The Rebels –an emergent group as stated in Quarantelli (2004)– became the voice of the dispersed population. Communication between Chaiteninos was possible due to a radio programme called “Chaiten Here” emitted from the city. Despite the difficulties, the first settlers adapted to the new situation while encourage other Chaiteninos to return. The Rebels perceived that the “exiled people” were under pressure to stay in their hosting cities by the psychologists provided by the Government in order to support them in the relocation process. Psychologists were instructed to tell people that “Chaiten was dead and they could never inhabit there again”. Both the Rebels and other Chaiteninos referred that situation as “brain washing” promoted by the authorities in an effort to elude facing the demands of the population (anonymous local leader, 2013, personal communication) (Rojas, 2013). In 2010, when the decision of relocating the city was still in course, authorities argued that it was essential to establish a dialogue with the community to make this project come true (Cifuentes, 2009). However, the community considered the initiative came too late and claimed that the new city was only in the imagination of planners and public authorities. People living in Chaiten also argued that they were not considered during the participation meetings held regarding the relocation project. However, MINVU (2010) asserts that 460 displaced people living in 14 localities participated during the planning process (Chaiten was not in the list). By end-2010, basic services were restored in the northern sector of Chaiten, the local and provincial Government returned to the city and a new investment Plan was announced to improve public infrastructure (Municipalidad de Chaitén, 2011). The first settler of the South returned in 2010 to her own house –she did not sell it through “Chaiten Law”–, and currently near 160 families occupy houses in the sector, claiming that there is no housing stock available in the North. During the last two years, those families have invested in repairing houses while no public services are 421 Vicente Sandoval et al. / Procedia Economics and Finance 18 ( 2014 ) 416 – 424 available. South residents have organized to get water and electricity, prorating the cost (around US$60/month per family). However, no organization exists to satisfy other needs such as transport, healthcare and education as well as to secure livelihoods. Furthermore, people describe the South sector as a “post-war” environment surrounded by demolished buildings and debris accumulation (see Figure 3). Many people in the South walk every day to the centre, where things are coming back to normal while they still demand for a bridge which connects again North and South. In both sectors of Chaiten, social organizations have emerged mainly to secure access to basic services. In the case of northern Chaiten, there are territorial organizations such as the neighbourhoods committees "Chaiten Alive" and "Pillan". In the South, organizations that stand out are rather functional because residents still have not secured their basic needs. According to some neighbours, the level of participation (in terms of Wilson, 2012) has fallen since northern organizations have obtained solutions to their claims. The same happens regarding risk perception as it has decay over time and less attention is paid to disaster risk reduction measures (Wisner et al., 2004), such as future evacuation plans. Chaiteninos mention that they do not trust in authorities anymore. They feel that Chaiten city could have been saved from floods if both people and authorities would have stayed during the eruption. “We would not evacuate again and future floods could be mitigated reinforcing the riverbed of the Blanco River” (anonymous local leader, 2013, personal communication). Although some mitigation measures were taken to protect the North edge of the new riverbed from floods and erosion, there are no studies about the South as none public investment in the area is permitted. In contrast to this, INFRACON (2012) asserts that despite mitigation measures may decrease the damage of frequent floods, the effects of an intense volcanic event as well as extreme floods could be catastrophic for the entire city. As the city is located in a highly exposed area, it is not clear how vulnerability may be reduced by mitigation measures. Although there are many Chaiteninos still in “exile”, not all of them will return to Chaiten as some have effectively integrated into other locations. Fig. 3 Part of demolished housing units in southern Chaiten 5. Beyond the volcano, unforeseen outcomes on resilience and environmental justice In Chaiten, political decisions taken and policies’ effects have dramatically eroded people’s ability to learn from and adapt to disasters. In that sense, an example is provided by unforeseen effects resulting from the monthly social 422 Vicente Sandoval et al. / Procedia Economics and Finance 18 ( 2014 ) 416 – 424 benefit named Bono Emergencia Chaiten and the one-off housing subsidy delivered by MINVU. During the two years of the emergency benefits, according to some local officers, people turned literally “crazy” due to the amount of money. “Prior to 2008, people used to live with so much less [...] when they received ʻthatʼ amount of money many people wasted it in holidays, travelling and expensive clothing” (anonymous public employee, 2013, personal communication). When benefits ran out, the bulk of people found themselves without savings, with debts and some with psychological problems (Paz, 2011, Sáez, 2009). In other words, while on the one hand benefits brought help and support for affected people during the crisis, on the other hand, benefits eroded community resilience by disarticulating people’s livelihoods and producing dependency on Government support, thus threatening people’s ability to react from and recover from disasters (Schilderman and Lyons, 2010) The same logic applies to other circumstances where both community and local authorities’ actions –and inactions– exacerbated the unequal distribution of environmental risks –mainly related to floods and to volcanic hazards–, vulnerability and resilience. The divided city of Chaiten not only resulted as consequence of nature but it was accentuated by policies and responses. For instance, the institutional incapacity –i.e. at municipal and regional level– for managing and promoting resilience revealed how governance centralization may limit community and local authorities’ actions. For one year since the disaster, the Government created and maintained a special authority, the Presidential Delegate, which aimed to support displaced families but also competed with regional and local authorities on the rehabilitation of Chaiten (Allard, 2010). The tension created by this special authority affected people’s trust in authorities as much as erratic decisions of declaring Chaiten “dead” and then “alive” again. The same inconsistent attitude also feeds people’s hopes for seeing South sector declared inhabitable again, perpetuating uncertainty among the population. The community’s demand for a bridge that connect North and South as well as flooding protection for the southern edge of the riverbed remains unattended as volcanic hazard provides an excuse. Ironically, Municipality, the Regional Government and recently the National Government have shown signs on the change of the South’s political status (Jara and Baeza, 2012) by investing in the area –i.e. an approved street lighting project for 2013 and a playground already implemented–. While the environmental injustice in Chaiten can be expressed through the way in which the southern sector is disproportionally more exposed than the North, the resilience of Chaiten population –as a whole– has been and is being eroded by political decisions. As mentioned above, only marginal attempts for promoting resilience within people in the South have been implemented by the Government. “Chaiten population are poorer than 2008 and less self-organized than 2010” (anonymous high municipal officer, 2013, personal communication). Inversely, as Schilderman and Lyons point out (2010), the environmental injustice of the spatial distribution of risk may also be shaped by decisions taken to increase the resilience of the city. For instance, while Regional government started demolition works of housing units in the South in order to avoid more occupations in the area –and thus reducing the number of people exposed to hazards–, all new housing projects in the North were abruptly ended (Baeza, 2013). General and specific political forces may shape the way in which processes of environmental justice and resilience interact within the Chaiten post-disaster context. As presented throughout this paper, political actions should not be considered as mere underlying factors of disasters (Pelling, 2006, Wisner et al., 2004) but determinants for defining the exposure to and ability to recover from hazardous events. As explored above, community responses to policies and decisions taken in a post-disaster context have resulted in resisting actions to and erosion-of-trust in authorities and in the public sector. 423 Vicente Sandoval et al. / Procedia Economics and Finance 18 ( 2014 ) 416 – 424 6. References Allard, P., 2010. ‘Fables of Reconstruction: Chaitén, After the Volcano’, Revista Harvard Review of Latina America, 9 (2), 36-38. Baeza, A., 2013. A cinco años de la erupción del volcán Chaitén: los logros y los proyectos de una ciudad que estuvo cerca de desaparecer [press release], 23 Apr, available: http://goo.gl/ocp47P [accessed 22 Aug 2013]. Cifuentes, C., 2009. Delegada presidencial inicia proceso informativo por reubicación de Chaitén [press release], 25 Feb, available: http://www.latercera.com/contenido/680_104618_9.shtml [accessed 19 Aug 2013]. CIMM T&S Consultores, 2010. Estudio de contaminación de cenizas y suelos en la ciudad de chaitén y propuesta de medidas de mitigación y restauración, Santiago de Chile: SEREMI Salud Región de Los Lagos. Cutter, S. L., Barnes, L., Berry, M., Burton, C., Evans, E., Tate, E. and Webb, J., 2008. ‘A place-based model for understanding community resilience to natural disasters’, Global Environmental Change, 18 (4), 598-606. De la Barrera, F., Reyes-Paecke, S. and Meza, L., 2011. ‘Landscape analysis for rapid ecological assessment of relocation alternatives for a devastated city’, Revista Chilena De Historia Natural, 84 (2), 181-194. El Mercurio, 2013. Chaitén, a cinco años de dura erupción [press release], 29 Apr, available: http://goo.gl/IVRuPD [accessed 21 Aug 2013]. El Mercurio en Internet, 2010. Piñera corrige al intendente de Los Lagos y asegura que Nueva Chaitén se emplazará en Santa Bárbara [press release], 27 May, available: http://goo.gl/IemHg5 [accessed 21 Aug 2013]. EM-DAT, 2013. 'Chile Country Profile' [online], available: http://www.emdat.be/result-country-profile Gobierno Regional de Los Lagos – GORE, 2008. Decreto Supremo Nº 588 del 02 de Mayo de 2008 que Señala como afectada por la catástrofe a la Provincia de Palena, Puerto Montt: Ministerio del Interior. Gobierno Regional de Los Lagos – GORE, 2009. Criterios en el Proceso de Asignación del Bono de desplazamiento víctimas del Volcán Chaitén, Puerto Montt: Ministerio del Interior. Gobierno Regional de Los Lagos – GORE, 2010. Criterios en el Proceso de Asignación del Bono de desplazamiento víctimas del Volcan Chiatén 2010, Puerto Montt: Ministerio del Interior. INFRACON S.A., 2012. Estudio de riesgo de sismos, volcanismo, remoción en masa, inundación por desborde de cauces y canales y maremotos para ocho localidades de la comuna de Chaitén, Informe Final, Santiago de Chile: SUBDERE. Instituto Nacional de Estadísticas de Chile INE, 2002. Censo, Santiago de Chile: INE. Intendencia Región de Los Lagos, 2010. 'Informó el intendente Montes: Declaración sobre habitabilidad de Chaitén', Gobierno de Chile [online], available: http://www.intendencialoslagos.gov.cl/n154_10-12-2010.html [accessed 21 Aug 2013]. Jara, A. and Baeza, M., 2012. 'Alcalde defiende gestión de atender a familias que viven en Chaitén Sur pese a no estar habilitado', BioBioChile.cl [online], available: http://rbb.cl/2p16 [accessed 03 Aug 2013]. La Nación, 2009. Edmundo Pérez Yoma: "Chaitén desgraciadamente ha muerto" [press release], 20 Feb, available: http://goo.gl/kt66ob [accessed 1 Aug 2013]. Lara, L. E., 2009. ‘The 2008 eruption of the Chaitén Volcano, Chile : A preliminary report’, Andean geology, 36, 125-129. Mardones, R., Rueda, S. and Guzmán, M., 2011. ‘Tejiendo vínculos: una mirada a la organización “renacer de Chaitén” de la tercera edad en un contexto de posdesastre’, Cuadernos de Crisis y Emergencias, 2 (10), 19-40. Ministerio de Vivienda y Urbanismo MINVU, 2010. Plan Maestro Ciudad de Chaitén: Informe Final, Santiago de Chile: MINVU. Moreno, H. and Lara, L., 2008. Peligros volcánicos potenciales del volcán Chaitén, Región de Los Lagos, Santiago de Chile: SERNAGEOMIN. Moreno, H., Lara, L., Arenas, M. and Derch, P., 2008. Evaluación preliminar de los peligros geológicos en la ciudad de Chaitén, Provincia de Palena, región de Los Lagos, Santiago de Chile: SERNAGEOMIN. Municipalidad de Chaitén, 2011. Reconstrucción de Chaitén, Santiago de Chile: Gobierno Regional de Los Lagos. Paz, V., 2011. Deudas, miedo y abandono, la otra cara del Chaitén [press release], 11 Jan, available: http://goo.gl/3i2l9A [accessed 11 Mar 2012]. Pelling, M., 2006. Natural disasters as catalysts of political action, ISP/NSC briefing paper, 06 (01), 4-6. Pontificia Universidad Católica de Chile PUC, Observatorio de Ciudades PUC, Universidad Austral de Chile and ARUP, 2009. Consultoría para el desarrollo de lineamientos estratégicos de reconstrucción / relocalización y Plan Maestro conceptual post-desastre Chaitén, Santiago de Chile: PUC. Presidencia de la República de Chile, 2009. Cuenta Pública de la Delegada Presidencial Paula Narváez en Chaitén, Santiago de Chile: Gobierno de Chile. Quarantelli, E. L., 2004. 'Emergent behaviors and groups in the crisis time periods of disasters', Preliminary Paper - University of Delaware, Disaster Research Center working paper, No. 206, 1-8. Ramirez, N., 2010. Alcalde de Chaitén: ¡En Talcahuano sabrán que nosotros llevamos dos años sin agua! [press release], 10 May, available: http://goo.gl/YpKn02 [accessed 11 Mar 2012]. 424 Vicente Sandoval et al. / Procedia Economics and Finance 18 ( 2014 ) 416 – 424 Rojas, J., 2013. La reconquista de Chaitén [press release], 23 Jul, available: http://www.theclinic.cl/2013/07/23/la-reconquista-de-chaiten/ [accessed 30 Jul 2013]. Sáez, M. E., 2009. 'Chaitén: ¿Por qué resistimos? Un testimonio de las familias que permanecen en Chaitén', Part 1 of 11 [Ethnographic documentary], available: http://goo.gl/aBNXAW [30 Apr 2012]. Schilderman, T. and Lyons, M., 2010. ‘Resilient dwellings or resilient people? Towards people-centred reconstruction’, Environmental Hazards, 10 (3-4), 218-231. SERNAGEOMIN, 2009. Erupción del Volcán Chaitén: Informes técnicos Mayo 2008-Marzo de 2009, Santiago de Chile: SERNAGEOMIN. Silva, S., 2010. 'Piñera asegura que Chaitén será reubicado en localidad de Santa Bárbara', Radio Universidad de Chile [online], available: http://goo.gl/aCzJmn [accessed 20 Jul 2013]. Walker, G. P. and Bulkeley, H., 2006. ‘Geographies of Environmental Justice’, Geoforum, 37 (5), 655-659. Wilson, G. A., 2012. ‘Community resilience, policy corridors and the policy challenge’, Land Use Policy, 31 (0), 298-310. Wisner, B., Blaikie, P., Cannon, T. and Davis, I., 2004. At risk : natural hazards, people's vulnerability, and disasters, 2nd ed., London ; New York: Routledge. work_6tgd6mmkunfvtensx2zee6dote ---- UCL Judicial Institute - UCL – University College London Close UCL Home Prospective students Current students Staff Give UCL Judicial Institute Home Home About People Events Research Publications Contact Us UCL Home UCL Judicial Institute Home About People Events Research Publications Contact Us Home About People Events Research Publications Contact Us UCL Home UCL Judicial Institute UCL Judicial Institute The UCL Judicial Institute is the UK's first and only centre of excellence devoted to research, teaching and policy engagement about the judiciary Groundbreaking  Carrying out groundbreaking research, teaching and policy development to promote understanding of the judiciary and a fair and effective judicial system Research  Conducting cutting-edge and interdisciplinary research on the judiciary that has a high policy impact     Teaching Pioneering teaching in judicial studies that brings students in direct contact with judges and policy-makers Professional development  Creating new professional development programmes about judges and the judicial process for lawyers in practice Public debate  Serving as a public forum to address key issues facing judges and courts worldwide International Conducting comparative judicial research and serving on international organisations devoted to understanding and improving the judicial process Judges Groundbreaking research about and with judges exploring judicial decision-making, appointments, education and the judicial process Juries  Landmark research on the jury system in this country by the UCLJury Project, examining the fairness of the jury system and working exclusively with real jurors at court Tribunals  Path-breaking empirical research on perceptions of tribunals and the fairness of tribunal decision-making Judicial diversity  Leading on research and policy development on how to achieve a more representative judiciary Future justice  Addressing the legal, social and technological challenges facing  judges and courts in the 21st century Civil justice  World-renowned expertise on the civil justice system and the public use of the legal system Contact us Email: judicialinstitute@ucl.ac.uk Tel: 020 3108 8485 Address: UCL Faculty of Laws Bentham House 4-8 Endsleigh Gardens London WC1H 0EG Find us on Google Maps Watch Purple Haze: Professor C Thomas give Inaugural Lecture (YouTube) Download Dominic Grieve's speech on "Why Conservatives Need the ECHR" [pdf]  CPD Course Programme "Understanding Judging" [pdf]  36th F A Mann Lecture by Professor Dame Hazel Genn [pdf]    UCL facilities About UCL Faculties and departments Library Museums and Collections UCL Bloomsbury Theatre UCL Shop UCL locations Maps and buildings UCL and London UCL Global Connect with UCL Alumni Businesses Media Relations Jobs Support us University College London, Gower Street, London, WC1E 6BT Tel: +44 (0) 20 7679 2000 Copyright © 2021 UCL Disclaimer Freedom of Information Accessibility Privacy and Cookies Slavery statement Contact Us work_6uoaqa6pxza3tfmjem2mzzcpvu ---- Lifestyle, responsibility and justice E Feiring Correspondence to: E Feiring, Postdoctoral research fellow, Department of Political Science, University of Oslo, PO Box 1097 Blindern, N-0317 Oslo, Norway; eli.feiring@stv.uio.no Received 7 September 2006 Revised 30 November 2006 Accepted 6 December 2006 Unhealthy lifestyle contributes significantly to the burden of disease. Scarce medical resources that could alternatively be spent on interventions to prevent or cure sufferings for which no one is to blame, are spent on prevention or treatment of (the risk of) disease that could be avoided through individual lifestyle changes. This may encourage policy makers and health care professionals to opt for a criterion of individual responsibility for medical suffering when setting priorities. The following article asks whether responsibility-based reasoning should be accepted as relevant for fair and legitimate healthcare rationing. The luck- egalitarian argument that inequalities in health expectancies that derive from unchosen features of people’s circumstances are unjust and should be compensated, while inequalities that reflect perso- nal choices of lifestyle may not, is discussed. It seems that while a backward-looking interpreta- tion of individual responsibility cannot be relevant as a criterion of priority setting, a forward-looking conception of responsibility may be approved. Within all modern societies healthcare autho- rities are facing difficult priority setting problems. Various criteria for rationing medical intervention have been proposed due to scarcity of resources. Until now, individual responsibility for medical suffering has been given little attention in the public or in academic debate. This is about to change. As Alexander Cappelen and Ole Norheim have pointed out in a recent article in this journal, unhealthy lifestyle contributes increasingly to the burden of disease. A better understanding of the responsibility argument is important for the assessment of policies aimed at meeting this challenge.1 In this article the following question is addressed: should responsibility-based arguments be accepted as relevant to meeting healthcare rationing fairly and legitimately? I will argue that while a backward-looking conception of individual responsibility should not be endorsed, a forward- looking notion of responsibility may be approved. RESPONSIBILITY AND JUST ALLOCATION OF HEALTHCARE There are both empirical and theoretical reasons for why it is time to ask whether people in developed countries should be held responsible for their health and if so, how a criterion of responsibility should be applied as a limit-setting device when deciding whether or not a particular medical intervention should be part of public healthcare and how to set priorities among patients. As reported by the World Health Organization (WHO), most of the risk factors contributing to the burden of disease can be attributed to unhealthy lifestyle.2 Thus, one of the major challenges for healthcare authorities in liberal-democratic welfare states seems to be the fact that scarce resources are spent on treatment of medical sufferings that, at least to some degree, could be avoided through individual lifestyle changes. Theoretically, there has been a shift in the general ideal of equality of opportunity from the traditional ideal of equality of condition to an ideal of equality that incorporates responsibility by compensating individuals for unequal circum- stances while holding them responsible for their choices. The view that egalitarianism is based on a concern with a choice-oriented view of responsi- bility may be labelled luck-egalitarianism.3 Although this view is expressed somewhat differ- ently among scholars, the core ideas are as follows.4–6 The concern of distributive justice is ‘‘to eliminate so far as possible the impact on people’s lives of bad luck that falls on them through no fault or choice of their own’’.7 Inequalities generated by the individual’s volun- tary choices are, however, acceptable and do not give rise to redistributive claims on others. Nobody is required to mitigate the effects of these choices. The principle of responsibility implies that society ought to distribute goods and burdens in a way that is luck-neutralising and choice-sensi- tive. When applied on issues of just allocation of healthcare, the principle suggests that inequalities in health expectancies that stem from differences in lifestyle that reflect personal priorities are justified, and might not be compensated. A back- ward-looking interpretation of individual responsi- bility for (high risk of) deviations from normal functioning would imply that people should be held responsible for their medical condition in virtue of their prior conduct. It is, however, not obvious exactly what this means. The answer to this question is highly important when deciding whether there are good reasons to accept a back- ward-looking conception of individual responsibil- ity when making decisions on priority setting within healthcare. THE CASE OF OBESITY Consider the case of obesity. As reported by the WHO, obesity (body mass index.30) has become an epidemic and leads to increased risks of coronary heart disease, stroke, type 2 diabetes, osteoarthritis, and several cancers.2 The increased incidence of obesity cannot be blamed on either environment or genetics alone. Increase in caloric intake and decrease in physical activity are primarily responsible for it, although genetic back- ground, maternal weight, and socioeconomic sta- tus are important.8 Both prevention and treatment of obesity are necessary means to reduce risk of severe disease Law, ethics and medicine J Med Ethics 2008;34:33–36. doi:10.1136/jme.2006.019067 33 o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://jm e .b m j.co m / J M e d E th ics: first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /jm e .2 0 0 6 .0 1 9 0 6 7 o n 2 1 D e ce m b e r 2 0 0 7 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://jme.bmj.com/ and premature death.9 For many, losing weight is difficult. It is shown that fewer than five percent of people who attempt diet and exercise recommendations succeed.10 Psychological inter- vention is often necessary to help obese patients initiate and maintain behaviour change.11–12 Alternatives are pharmacologic therapy for obesity, and surgery. SHOULD LIFESTYLE CHOICES AFFECT PRIORITY SETTING? Now, let us assume that we live in a developed country with a universal coverage healthcare system with no supplementary tier that is purchased by those who are best off in society. There is no private healthcare insurance available. Trivially, the assumptions of scarcity and opportunity costs apply. Public healthcare resources are scarce and time and technology invested to provide a given medical intervention always have an alternative usage within (and without) the public healthcare system. We are engaged in the deliberation on whether a particular intervention i1 to treat obesity for the purpose of reducing risk r1 of severe disease x should be part of public healthcare, and whether information on lifestyle and body mass index should be given weight (if at all) when setting priorities among patients waiting for a particular medical intervention i2 to treat a severe disease x (associated with lifestyle-induced risk r1 as well as non-lifestyle induced risks r2, r3…). The following arguments are put forward. First, if obesity is rightly attributed to individual lifestyle choices, i1 should not be covered within the public healthcare system. Second, i2 should be allocated according to a priority-rule that assigns longer waiting time to patients suffering from x as a result of individual lifestyle choices (contributing to r1), than for patients suffering from x as a result of factors not within their control (contributing to r2, r3...). The luck-egalitarian mode of reasoning may explain the intuitions behind these arguments. If lifestyle preferences are formed under conditions of justice and circumstantial differ- ences in opportunity to choose a healthy lifestyle are neutralised through preventive means, then outcomes that are suitably related to one’s choices (option luck) need not be compensated. The individual may be asked to bear the costs of engaging in risky behaviour.13 Although it is difficult to avoid risk altogether, she may be held responsible for not choosing the least risky prospect.14 Differences in people’s access to treatment should be allowed when they are due to differences in lifestyle choices. It seems, however, that it would not be reasonable to hold people wholly responsible for outcomes that reflect option luck in these matters. Obesity may not adequately explain why some get a (face a high risk of) severe disease x and others do not, because (high risk of) disease is an outcome partly determined by occurrence of events we cannot reasonably avoid the possibility of (brute luck). It may, then, be wrong to deny any claims on society to provide an intervention i1 to treat obesity for the purpose of reducing risk r1 of severe disease x. Nevertheless, these claims would be weak and may be overridden by competing claims when allocating healthcare resources. Accordingly, the obese patient suffering from x should not be held wholly responsible for her situation at the sick bed and be denied treatment. Assigning longer waiting time for treatment to obese patients than to their normal-weight counterparts may be one way of holding people partly responsible for their lifestyle choices. To sum up: If the individual can reasonably be held responsible for (high risk of) deviations from normal functioning due to obesity, she has weak claims on society to provide specialized medical intervention within a limited healthcare budget. DISCUSSION: INDIVIDUAL RESPONSIBILITY REJECTED? Do we have sufficient reason to accept limit-setting according to this line of argumentation as fair and legitimate? I think the answer is no. In general, the luck-egalitarian position has been criticised for a number of reasons that I cannot pursue in any depth here.3 15–21 Let me briefly make four points. First, it appears to be a flaw to ground the idea of egalitarianism on the distinction between choices and circum- stances. As Samuel Scheffler has pointed out, this distributive formula must be part of a larger normative theory.20 Unless the category of choice is explained as distinctive in a way that makes it a privileged indicator of the fairness or unfairness of an outcome, it is difficult to understand why it should have such a fundamental importance as it has within luck-egalitarianism. Second, the choice-circumstances dichotomy seems implausible, because choices may better be thought of as simultaneously autonomous and socialised.17 20 21 It is hard to identify any action that is not partly determined by circumstance under- stood as the social contexts in which the individual finds herself or her traits of character (included the ability to choose). It is not obvious, then, what it means that someone may reasonably be held responsible for her actions. Third, although people may be held responsible for their choices in the sense of being open to moral criticism for negligence or high-risk behaviour, this does not imply that they are not entitled to any assistance.3 15 20 Issues of what people are to be held responsible for should be distinguished from issues of how deserving they are. In Susan Hurley’s words, responsibility cannot play a pattering role.18 Fourth, luck-egalitarianism may promote the wrong ‘‘ethos of equality’’.16 As Elizabeth Anderson has forcefully put the argument:3 (T)he social process of distinguishing responsible from irresponsible, deserving from non-deserving citizens is inher- ently disrespectful and unfair to all members of society (…). (T)aking the imperative of justice to be undoing the effects of all brute bad luck inherently erases the line between what is the legitimate concern of society and what should be left to individual discretion. Healthcare is a special good When considering the backward-looking concept of individual responsibility within the healthcare context, I think there are reasons external to the luck-egalitarian position that may explain why it is so important to pay attention to these critical points. The core of the argument is that healthcare is a special good and should not be allocated to eliminate the impact of bad brute luck or to ensure that everyone gets what they morally deserve. As Norman Daniels has pointed out, what makes healthcare special is its role in establishing fair equality of opportunity.22 23 The proper aim of healthcare allocation is to contribute to protect (age-relative) opportunity for participa- tion in society on a roughly equal footing. Disability and disease reduce the range of opportunities to exert citizenship that people would otherwise enjoy. The idea of equal citizenship is part of the liberal-contractual notion of society as a fair system of cooperation among free and equal people. Equality is an ideal that governs the terms of cooperation, and is not solely a distributive notion.20 Law, ethics and medicine 34 J Med Ethics 2008;34:33–36. doi:10.1136/jme.2006.019067 o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://jm e .b m j.co m / J M e d E th ics: first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /jm e .2 0 0 6 .0 1 9 0 6 7 o n 2 1 D e ce m b e r 2 0 0 7 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://jme.bmj.com/ The implication of this argument is that healthcare allocation must be defended and criticised in terms of consideration that others, free and equal, have reasons to accept, given the fact of reasonable pluralism and on the assumption that those others are themselves committed to provide suitable justification.24 Citizens are entitled to make claims on one another by virtue of their status as citizens. This means that one needs to find reasons for just allocation that are compelling to all - accordingly motivated - regardless of their diverse commit- ments, natural attributes or social starting-points. Rejecting the backward-looking conception of individual responsibility In my view, the luck-egalitarian underpinnings of the back- ward-looking responsibility conception fail to appreciate this concern. It is simply not reasonable that the distinction between choices and circumstances have fundamental impor- tance for questions of how to ration scarce healthcare resources as in the case of obesity. The explanation is that the ‘‘irresponsible’’ minority can hardly assure itself that the preferences of the ‘‘responsible’’ majority rests on the kind of reason that even the minority must acknowledge as appro- priate. Let me give two examples (that resemble the criticism against luck-egalitarianism made as point two and four described above). The backward-looking responsibility conception tells us to find a way to split compensation between people according to which extent they can be held properly responsible for their choices. The diversion requires an explanation of what is to count as choice and what is to count as circumstance that must be acceptable to all. In the literature, there is vast disagreement on where to draw the line.20 What appears to be difficult in ideal theory is even more so in the context of healthcare where social and economic inequalities are very important in determining health expectancies. Obesity is not evenly distributed across the population. As Brian Barry has pointed out, poverty, class and income are key-determinates of obesity and weight-related disease.25 It may not, then, be reasonable to hold that lifestyle choices are informed and deliberate in the way that ought to be conditions for personal responsibility. Likewise, the decision on how to classify persons according to moral desert must be acceptable to all. There are at least two reasons why this requirement may be difficult to meet. To put focus on the distinction between choice and circumstances may encourage the state to view its disadvantaged citizens with distrust, as potential cheaters.16 26 The obese patient may have to prove she suffers from an involuntary disadvantage and answer questions about her own life as well as her family background that may be intrusive. One example is that she may be asked to submit to genetic testing, which may reveal information she (and her relatives) prefers to remain in ignorance of. Further, the majority may be encouraged to make moralised judgments in order to classify persons according to the degree of irresponsibility of their choices of food and activity. Moral categories may then be used in a simplistic way which ignores the complexity of the situation.20 A forward-looking conception of individual responsibility Would it be altogether wrong to consider individual responsi- bility when allocating scarce healthcare resources? Let us assume a deliberation process identical to the one described above. Remember the liberal-contractualist argument that the minority ought to assure itself that the preferences of the majority rest on the kind of reason that even the minority must acknowledge appropriate. This could mean to give priority to the worst off but only if significant health benefit is expected and treatment is cost-effective. Then the concept of medical need is interpreted according to both the pre-allocative and the expected post-allocative level of health.27 Even if this middle range priority position is indeterminate, I find it compelling. The reason is that it incorporates the concern for the most vulnerable without sacrificing greater health benefits to others.28 Giving priority to the most urgent cases without concern with efficacious use of limited resources may avoid abandonment of critically ill patients (which is likely to happen if maximising health benefit is all that matters) but only to the expense of the opportunities of health improvements of others. Accordingly, the consideration of individual responsibility would not be relevant when deciding whether or not i1 should be part of public healthcare. If obesity is (rightly) regarded as a significant predictor of severe illness and premature death and treatment is scientifically proven to be effective and cost- effective, treatment of obesity should be provided within public healthcare. But when we ask if an obese patient suffering from x should accept a longer wait than a normal-weight person to get access to elective medical intervention i2, I think the notion of individual responsibility may come into play. To see how, we must return to the criteria of priority setting. Severely ill patients who are likely to respond well to treatment (within given resource constraints) should, under the specified understanding of medical need, be given priority over patients less likely to benefit. Several factors may reduce expected benefit of treatment. While the individual has little or no power to influence some of these factors, she may be in a position to improve others. Factors attributed to lifestyle are among the latter. If the obese patient suffering from x does not change her lifestyle, then expected benefit from intervention i2 decreases and the patient will be given lower priority on the waiting list. TM Scanlon has argued that it seems that when a person has had an opportunity to avoid a certain outcome by choosing appropriately, this fact weakens her grounds for rejecting a principle that would make her bear the burden of that result. What matters is the value of the opportunity to choose that the person is presented with.15 I suggest that the obese patient suffering from x should be asked to sign a contract of frequent medical follow-ups to help her lose weight (in the same token as smokers with chronic obstructive lung disease should be asked to get medical advice on how to quit smoking and alcohol abusers with liver disease on how to stop drinking). If the patient refuses, then she cannot reasonably complain to be given lower priority on the waiting list. The point is not, then, to assess whether or not it would have been obtainable for one in the patient’s circumstances to make greater effort to get a healthy lifestyle in the past. She may or may not have had less opportunity than others not to make bad choices. Rather, the point is that when resources are limited we owe it each other to do what we can to make medical treatment efficacious. A priority scheme which includes the specified notion of responsibility may have unintended secondary consequences.27 Priority should be given according to the criteria of severity of disease and expected benefit of treatment. By giving lower priority to patients who are not expected to respond well to treatment due to continuous unhealthy lifestyle, the scheme Law, ethics and medicine J Med Ethics 2008;34:33–36. doi:10.1136/jme.2006.019067 35 o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://jm e .b m j.co m / J M e d E th ics: first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /jm e .2 0 0 6 .0 1 9 0 6 7 o n 2 1 D e ce m b e r 2 0 0 7 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://jme.bmj.com/ may also have the secondary effect of systematically giving patients from low social status-groups low priority because unhealthy lifestyle is associated with low social status. But this would be the case only if patients from low social status groups tend to refuse to sign the contract more often than others. We might say that the patient refuses to sign the contract because she does not really know what she is doing and that an unwillingness to comply should not be given weight when setting priorities. But this argument treats the patient as a less than an autonomous being. Given that respect for the autonomous choices of patients runs deep in modern health- care, there are strong reasons to value the claim that competent and well-informed individuals are the best interpreters of their own interest and that they should be free to make choices others would regard as non-beneficial to them.29 Of course, the contract may be broken and the priority decision may repeat itself, or the patient may not maintain her behaviour changes. These facts do not imply that further treatment (if necessary) should be denied. But others may simply have stronger claims on assistance. Thus, the forward- looking concept of responsibility described here is rather thin. It explains why responsibility-oriented arguments may be justified in a priority-setting context but it does not support the conclusion that people should be held substantively responsible for previous choices. Would this interpretation of the responsibility principle reproduce the problems rendering luck-egalitarian approaches unjust? I think not. First, rather than serve as a basis for just priority setting, the interpretation of the principle of responsi- bility is derived from a specific understanding of how to distribute healthcare. Second, we do not have to rely on a choice-circumstance binary to specify which inequalities are acceptable and which are not. Third, the fact that the individual’s medical need can be traced down to bad lifestyle does not imply that she should be denied healthcare. And fourth, I do not think it disrespectful to ask the individual to do what she can to change an unhealthy lifestyle to make treatment efficacious. Some may argue that it is unfair to add a burden upon those in medical need by asking them to sign a contract of medical follow-ups. The very question may even hurt the patient’s feelings, because one implicitly explains the disease with a reference to lifestyle. I do not, however, find these arguments strong enough to abandon individual respon- sibility-based arguments when estimating expected benefit of treatment. When deciding on the terms on which we want to live with one another, it is reasonable to expect people to make do with their fair shares. These are difficult issues, and I cannot discuss them further here. I have, however, provided a case for the claim that a forward-looking conception of individual responsibility may be approved. CONCLUDING REMARKS The liberal-contractual proposal for how to design deliberation to which persons are entitled to hold one another accountable about healthcare rationing puts constraints on the set of considerations that should be placed on the table when we ask how to allocate healthcare resources. As Norman Daniels has pointed out, what is important is to protect fair opportunity to participate in society and exert citizenship by meeting people’s medical needs within resource constraints.30 The question of justice within healthcare does not, then, concern the neutralisation of luck. Responsibility-based argu- ments may come into play, but only in a forward-looking version. Acknowledgements: Earlier drafts of this article have been presented at the workshop on Equality of Opportunity, ECPR Joint Sessions, Granada 2005, and at the workshop on Priority Setting in Global Health, University of Bergen, 2005. Thanks to all the participants. The article also benefited from comments of several friends and colleagues, among them Alexander Cappelen, Robert Huseby, Raino Malnes, and Ole Fr. Norheim. Thanks to Pierre Boitte and especially to Bob Brecher. Funding: The work for this article was made possible by a postdoctoral research grant from the Research Council of Norway. Competing interests: None declared. REFERENCES 1. Cappelen A, Norheim OF. Responsibility in health care - a liberal egalitarian approach. J Med Ethics 2005;31:476–80. 2. World Health Organization. The world health report: reducing risks, promoting healthy life. Geneva: WHO, 2002. 3. Anderson ES. What Is the Point of Equality? Ethics 1999;109:287–337. 4. Arneson R. Equality of Opportunity for Welfare. Philosophical Studies 1989;56:77– 93. 5. Cohen GA. On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice. Ethics 1989;99:906–44. 6. Roemer J. Equality of opportunity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1998. 7. Arneson R. Luck Egalitarianism and Prioritarianism. Ethics 2000;110:339–49. Cf. Temkin L. Inequality. New York: Oxford University Press, 1993. 8. Miller J, Rosenbloom A, Silverstein J. Childhood Obesity. J Clin Endocrinol Metab 2004;89:4211–18. 9. Mello MM, Studdert DM, Brennan T. Obesity – The New Frontier of Public Health Law. N Engl J Med 2006;354:2601–10. 10. Miller WC. How effective are traditional dietary and exercise interventions for weight loss? Med Sci Sports Exerc 1999;31:1129–34. 11. Wing RR, Tate DF, Gorin AA, et al. A Self-Regulation Program for Maintenance of Weight Loss. N Engl J Med 2006;335:1563–71. 12. Takeharu K, Atsushi K, Hisamichi A. Obesity and Public Health Law. N Engl J Med 2006;354:1283. 13. Vallentyne P. Brute Luck, Option Luck, and Equality of Initial Opportunities. Ethics 2002;112:529–57. 14. Sandbu M. On Dworkin’s brute-luck-option-luck distinction and the consistency of brute-luck egalitarianism. Politics, philosophy & economics 2004;3:283–312. 15. Scanlon TM. What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 1998. 16. Wolf J. Fairness, Respect, and the Egalitarian Ethos. Philosophy & Public Affairs 1998;27:97–122. 17. Mason A. Equality, personal responsibility and gender socialization. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 2000;100:227–46. 18. Hurley S. Roemer on Responsibility and Equality. Law and Philosophy 2002;21:39– 64. 19. Scheffler S. What is Egalitarianism? Philosophy & Public Affairs 2003;31:5–39. 20. Scheffler S. Choice, circumstance, and the value of equality. Politics, philosophy & economics 2005;4:5–28. 21. Phillips A. ‘‘Really’’ Equal: Opportunities and Autonomy. The Journal of Political Philosophy 2006;14:18–32. 22. Rawls J. Justice as Fairness. A restatement. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 2001. 23. Daniels N. Just Health Care. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,1985. 24. Cohen J. Democracy and Liberty. In: Elster J (ed).Deliberative Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998. 25. Barry B. Why Social Justice Matters. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press, 2005. 26. Kymlicka W. Contemporary Political Philosophy. An Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002. 27. Elster J. Local Justice. How Institutions Allocate Scarce Goods and Necessary Burdens.New York: Russel Sage Foundations, 1992. 28. Daniels N, Sabin JE. Setting Limits Fairly: Can We Learn to Share Medical Resources? New York: Oxford University Press, 2002. 29. Beauchamp TL, Childress JF. Principles of Biomedical Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press, 1994. 30. Daniels N. Justice, Health, and Healthcare. The American Journal of Bioethics 2001;1:2–16. Law, ethics and medicine 36 J Med Ethics 2008;34:33–36. doi:10.1136/jme.2006.019067 o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://jm e .b m j.co m / J M e d E th ics: first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /jm e .2 0 0 6 .0 1 9 0 6 7 o n 2 1 D e ce m b e r 2 0 0 7 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://jme.bmj.com/ work_6wjrvbztezdc7iui2ojyr2di5i ---- Middlesex University Research Repository An open access repository of Middlesex University research http://eprints.mdx.ac.uk Ruggiero, Vincenzo ORCID: https://orcid.org/0000-0002-4090-849X (2011) An abolitionist view of restorative justice. International Journal of Law, Crime and Justice, 39 (2) . pp. 100-110. ISSN 1756-0616 [Article] (doi:10.1016/j.ijlcj.2011.03.001) This version is available at: http://eprints.mdx.ac.uk/7831/ Copyright: Middlesex University Research Repository makes the University’s research available electronically. Copyright and moral rights to this work are retained by the author and/or other copyright owners unless otherwise stated. The work is supplied on the understanding that any use for commercial gain is strictly forbidden. A copy may be downloaded for personal, non-commercial, research or study without prior permission and without charge. Works, including theses and research projects, may not be reproduced in any format or medium, or extensive quotations taken from them, or their content changed in any way, without first obtaining permission in writing from the copyright holder(s). They may not be sold or exploited commercially in any format or medium without the prior written permission of the copyright holder(s). Full bibliographic details must be given when referring to, or quoting from full items including the author’s name, the title of the work, publication details where relevant (place, publisher, date), pag- ination, and for theses or dissertations the awarding institution, the degree type awarded, and the date of the award. If you believe that any material held in the repository infringes copyright law, please contact the Repository Team at Middlesex University via the following email address: eprints@mdx.ac.uk The item will be removed from the repository while any claim is being investigated. See also repository copyright: re-use policy: http://eprints.mdx.ac.uk/policies.html#copy http://eprints.mdx.ac.uk http://eprints.mdx.ac.uk/7831/ mailto:eprints@mdx.ac.uk http://eprints.mdx.ac.uk/policies.html#copy 1 An Abolitionist View of Restorative Justice Vincenzo Ruggiero Professor of Sociology, Middlesex University, London Abstract: Penal abolitionism is known for its unconventional analysis of crime, the law and punishment. Some critical views of restorative justice emerge when the alternatives to imprisonment advocated by abolitionists are examined. This paper discusses such views, highlighting their critique of professionalism and their emphasis on community conflict regulation. Keywords: abolitionism; restorative justice; professionalism; conflict regulation. Penal abolitionism is not merely a decarceration programme, but also an approach, a perspective, a methodology, and most of all a way of seeing. There is clearly an abolitionist element in the proposition that the state centralised administration of penal justice should be replaced by decentralised forms of autonomous conflict regulation. But in a general, concise, formulation it can be suggested that abolitionists advocate new ways of dealing with undesirable behaviour, and in doing so they situate themselves in an original position within the debate around restorative justice. If this is perhaps the major practical outcome, in terms of policy, with which abolitionist analysis can be associated, the specific components of their view on 2 restorative justice need to be spelled out. This is the task of the present paper (Bianchi, 1984, 1986, 1994; Christie, 1977, 1982, 1986a, 1986b, 1986c, 1993, 1996, 2004; Hulsman, 1982, 1986, 1991; Mathiesen, 1974, 1990, 2008; Ruggiero, 2010). Restitutive Sanctions Durkheim (1960: 111) associates restitutive sanctions to specific forms of social solidarity. What distinguishes such sanctions is that they are not expiatory, but consist, as he puts it, of means for reinstating the past. The social relationships regulated by the practice of restitution are quite different from those addressed by the repressive practices of the law. The former ‘unite the thing to the person’, while the latter ‘link persons among themselves’. Durkheim notes, in other words, that reconciliation may re-establish the relationships of individuals with their property rather than those with society at large. The image of society underpinning reconciliation and restitution is one of ‘an immense constellation where each star moves in its orbit without concern for the movements of neighbouring stars’. In such constellation solidarity does not make its components act together and contributes very little to ‘the unity of the social body’ (ibid: 116-117). Restitutive sanctions, therefore, do not ‘attach different parts of society to one another’; on the contrary, they clearly mark the barriers separating the different parts, doing nothing to create positive social links: ‘this is not a true solidarity’ (ibid: 119). Durkheim expresses views that echo some of the contemporary controversial concepts found in the debate around restorative justice. Restorative justice may be essentially defined as a process bringing the actors and communities affected by a problematic situation back into the condition in which the 3 problem arose. This model of justice implies that the parties involved decide how to deal with a conflict and how to neutralise its collective impact (Marshall, 1996). Restorative justice presents itself as an international network or movement, giving the impression that its tenets are diametrically opposed to those inspiring conventional retributive justice (Casey, 1999; Pollard, 2000; McLaughlin et al, 2003). Against such claim abolitionists are not alone in maintaining a critical stance (Williams, 2005). Participatory Disputes According to Hulsman (1991: 32), if we want to make progress in the efforts to create alternatives to custody, we have to abandon the cultural and social organisation of criminal justice. ‘Criminal justice is perpetrator-oriented, based on blame-allocation and on a last-judgement view on the world’. It therefore does not provide us with the necessary information relating to disputes, nor does it transform contexts in a way that emancipatory manners of dealing with disputes can be identified. First, an abolitionist approach is oriented towards those directly involved, namely persons or groups who directly experience unpleasant events, an approach leading to the discovery of the resources which could be mobilised to deal with such events and situations. Second, abolitionism must radically critique the idea that the extremely diverse situations currently criminalised possess something in common. The label ‘crime’ is attached to all kinds of different problems, which should be tackled by a variety of preventive measures. ‘To use punishment on all of them is comparable to treating all kinds of illness with leeches’ (Wright, 2008: 242). Each problem or event is characterised by its own contours and features, and information about these is a precondition for different understandings of the acts observed and the practical responses to them. On 4 the other hand, in order to design effective strategies of abolition and to project workable alternatives, Hulsman (1991: 35) intimates that ‘we need to agree on what we are opposing’. What we face now, in most societies, is a state-run organisation possessing the monopoly to define criminal behaviour, to prosecute that behaviour and to keep chosen individuals in confinement. This organisation, which is intended to protect society from those individuals, in reality, fails to accomplish what it promises. There are several procedures that can be used in dealing with trouble. Dumping is one of then, when the issue that gives rise to a disagreement is simply ignored and the relationship with the disagreeing person continues. Exit is another, an option that consists of withdrawing from the unpleasant situation and terminating the relationship with the other party. Then there may be negotiation, when the two parties attempt to settle the matter by identifying the rules that should govern their relationship. Mediation is yet another option, which involves the participation of a third party asked to help find an agreement. With arbitration, instead, the parties appoint a third actor and agree in advance to accept her judgement. With adjudication, finally, a third authority intervenes whether or not the two parties require so (Nader and Todd, 1978; Hulsman, 1986). Among these procedures abolitionists opt for those in which participants in conflicts are not constrained by the requirements of organisations or professionals. Flexibility, in this respect, is desirable, as it allows common meanings to emerge while giving the parties a possibility to learn about each other. Hulsman argues that flexibility is exactly what is lacking in conventional criminal justice, because situations are dealt with in highly formalised contexts, where definitions of issues and responses to them are limited, and it is unlikely that they correspond to those the parties involved would 5 elaborate. In brief, in his view, ‘trouble’ is to be turned into a participatory dispute by those experiencing it. Crime itself is a participatory dispute, and in abolitionist thought has to be defined in terms of tort. According to Bianchi (1986: 116), abolitionist purposes do not require that an entirely new system of rules be devised. ‘We already have one, waiting to be applied and adapted’. Lawyers and jurists, in this sense, are natural allies of the abolitionists, since they are capable, and hopefully willing, ‘to develop new concepts of tort which would be suitable for the regulation of crime conflicts, and rules for the settlement of disputes arising from what we used to call crime’. Bianchi appeals to psychologists, psychiatrists and social workers, calling for their skills to be adapted and rewritten in ways fit for conflict-regulation. ‘The new system would no longer be called criminal law but reparative law’, and would engage offenders in discussions around the harm caused and how it can be repaired (ibid). Offenders would be debtors: ‘Guilt and culpability should be replaced by debt, liability and responsibility’ (Bianchi, 1994: xi). It is among the contentions of abolitionists that an entirely different system of crime control, including restorative forms of justice, necessitates entirely new linguistic terms, in order to prevent conventional reasoning from creeping in. To make a new system of conflict resolution stand out against the conventional punitive system, Bianchi introduces one such term, eunomic. This adjective is opposed to anomic and alienating which denote the nature of the official criminal justice system, and which frustrate the main participants in a conflict; the new system would be mainly composed of a set of integrative rules offering opportunities to all participants (Bianchi, 1994). This argument takes inspiration from Roman Law, whose eunomic nature is epitomised by the central role played in it by restitution. The very Latin word 6 poena (from which both pain and punishment derive) refers less to the type or intensity of the punishment to be inflicted than to the obligation to compensate the victim. Before its modern translation into physical pain, poena alludes to the penalty to be paid directly to the injured party, rather than to the vengeful sufferance inflicted by the state. Even the original meaning of the Latin verb punire is ‘see to it that the duty of poena be fulfilled’, for an offender could usually buy off revengeful punishment by settling the compensation. Knowledge, Proximity and Dialogue If the official criminal justice system lacks libido sciendi, a passion for knowledge, the alternatives to punishment devised by abolitionism are designed with the purpose of producing that knowledge and collate information about actors involved in conflicts. Consequently, the forms of restorative justice criticised by abolitionism are those which, physically and metaphorically, are distant from the settings where conflicts take place. Professionalism attracts particularly vehement criticism. The enormous expansion in the number of professionals trained for dealing with other people’s behavioural problems has created a range of functionaries, ‘most of them working in bureaucracies, from nine to four, with short encounters with clients’. Such professionals will not experience the consequences of their decisions; after work ‘they will drive home to the suburbs, to partners and children and dogs’ (Christie, 1982: 67-68). Their power consists of their alleged capacity to respond to conflicts, reduce their effects and prevent future conflicts from erupting. In order to control that power, Christie argues, those wielding it are to be made vulnerable, a task that can be achieved if they are denied the specificity of their qualifications and the peculiarity of 7 their status, and ultimately if they are required to live emotionally and physically in proximity to the situations with which they deal. Professionals who do not share the settings of conflicts seem to be convinced that all conflicts are to be solved or managed. Abolitionism talks about conflict-handling, or ‘conflict participation’, regarded as more promising, in concrete social interactions, than solutions. ‘Conflicts are not necessarily a bad thing. They can also be seen as something of value, a commodity not to be wasted. Conflicts are not in abundance in a modern society: they are a scarcity. They are in danger of being lost, or often stolen. The victim in a criminal case is a sort of double loser: first vis-à-vis the offender, secondly vis-à-vis the state. He is excluded from any participation in his own conflict.’ (ibid: 93). This appreciation of conflict reminds one of Simmel’s (1950) argument that attraction and repulsion are the core elements of socialisation, and that degrees of both contribute to processes of unification. Abolitionism translates this argument into a description of crime as a communicative act, expressive conduct, ‘a clumsy attempt to say something’. Hence the suggestion that crime should ‘become a starting point for a real dialogue, and not for an equally clumsy answer in the form of a spoonful of pain’ (Christie, 1982: 11). Existing systems, with their professional division of roles, hamper dialogue, allowing for many acts to be perceived as crime. Alternative systems, therefore, should be arranged so that the same acts are more easily seen as expressions of conflicting interests. ‘To reduce man-inflicted pain, one should encourage the construction of the latter type of systems’ (ibid). 8 Dialogue encouraged by proximity is a key strategy suggested by abolitionists with a view to producing knowledge about problematic situations. In this respect, it is worthwhile to follow Christie’s argument in a clarifying example. Let us imagine a computer deciding on guilt and delivering sentences. If correctly programmed, the computer will reach infallible decisions. ‘After guilt was decided, nobody would need to attend before the judge to listen to his decisions if they themselves had some mini- computers at their disposal. This means that chance is taken away from court- decisions’ (Christie, 1982: 54). There is, however, another possibility, namely the re- programming of the computer, a circumstance which would show how imperfect the decision-making technology may be. What are the variables that would be given priority weight? And most importantly, who would decide exactly what input is to be inserted into the system? The following are some possibilities: ‘The UN in the General Assembly; the UN in the Crime Committee; regional bodies such as the European Council or the Union of the Arab States; national parliaments; regional authorities; a random sample of the population questioned through the telephone or personal interviews; a sample from the municipality of the victim or the offender; a totality of those close to the victim or the offender; or decisions could be made by the victim and the offender in cooperation’ (Christie, 1982: 55-56) Proceeding from top to bottom, the various actors listed above, all hypothetically able to provide input to our sentencing computer, possess increasing familiarity and proximity with the parties involved in the conflict. With the last option, however, we are faced with the maximum degree of proximity, and it is with this option that our 9 computer would become totally redundant, as the parties concerned could talk directly to each other. Knowledge acquired by professionals differs from that informing interactions in lived experience, in the subterranean pattern of information shared within communities. It is plausible to assume that the quantity and nature of information held by members of a group will make sweeping concepts such as ‘crime’ needless to that group. This will be determined less by the size of the group than by the intensity of the common history the group shares. Small societies with little shared history and limited mutual knowledge and information about members will express demands for behaviour uniformity. For example, ‘dormitory towns’ will tend to turn the lack of interactions among its inhabitants and the absence of a common history among them into simplistic definitions of the others and their actions. It is against such aggregations of strangers that powerful, distant, institutions deliver pain. ‘Intentional infliction of pain is easier the further away the recipient is from the delivery-man’ (ibid: 83). Victims It has been suggested that restorative justice, by encouraging encounters between parties involved in conflict, benefits the victim’s mental health by reducing post- traumatic stress symptoms (Strang, 2002; Braithwaite, 2007). Abolitionism holds a different view on the subject matter: victims can be victimised by conventional victimology itself. In other words, they can become the victims of the stereotypes imposed upon them. These stereotypes relate to their alleged incapacity to defend themselves, but also to their inability to define themselves as victims, the condition of 10 victim being granted by others despite them. Subsequently, those victimised by conventional victimology are regarded and treated as objects of tutelage, as ‘judicial goods’ who are required not to interfere with the situation in which they act. They are requested to entrust their inviolability to external agencies which are normally structured to reproduce principles of dependency and delegation, rather than principles of autonomy. While conventional victimology and conventional restorative justice, therefore, may use victims’ participation as a tool for the strengthening of the penal system, resulting in ‘increased fear of crime, daily demands for stiffer sentences, and a steep increase in levels of criminological nonsense’ (Carlen, 1996: 53), abolitionism combines victims’ participation with non-penal measures, informality, negotiation and community involvement. Compensation as devised by abolitionists, for example, is not based on abstract variables such as judicial truth, guilt or dangerousness, but on the responsibilities of the offenders, the victims, the community as a whole, and on their respective needs. In this exercise of justice there are no winning or losing contestants, as all are involved in a healing process aimed at satisfying the basic requirement for collective wellbeing and safety. The solution proposed by Christie (1982: 84-85) is that ‘those given the task of handling the conflict are not given power’, but play a mediatory role, like ‘the dwarf at the royal court’ who was so powerless and ‘small that he was unusually well suited as a go-between’; or as a child who can at times take on a similar role in a family conflict. In brief, such figures should act as independent third parties and would be ‘asked to help, but not given authority to enforce, and with no possibility of personal gain related to the outcome of the conflict’ (ibid). Restorative justice in the abolitionist perspective is not aimed at ‘restoring’ the situation preceding the conflict, but at clarifying values during the course of its exercise: ‘The clarification of values is 11 accomplished in the process itself. Attention is moved away from the end-result to the process’ (ibid: 94). We must concede that abolitionism occupies a highly original position within the influential victims’ movement which developed since the 1970s. While victims of crime have long lamented the failure of the criminal justice system to keep them informed, and campaigns have targeted the arbitrary distinction between deserving and undeserving victims, institutional responses have been confined to the provision of governmentally centralised compensation schemes. In this way, victims become increasingly characterised as users, clients or consumers; and in some circumstances they are even given the privilege to attend the execution of those who victimised them (Rock, 2004; Williams, 2005). Abolitionists reject such consumerist logic, regarding it as an aspect of ‘industrialised justice’ in which distant authorities keep playing a key role in responding to problems. The participatory model they advocate puts institutional agencies out of the limelight, in their reparatory as well as their adjudicative functions. On the other hand, the victims’ movement has also been concerned with forms of conflict resolution that, initially tailored for the needs of the victims, in practice have turned out to be mainly designed for the welfare of offenders. In this way, the discovery of the victims, in reality, is alleged to have provided a good pretext for reformers to espouse increasingly lenient treatment for victimisers. A ‘good deal for offenders’ is therefore assumed to be the outcome of victim-focused justice, ‘a back door to the introduction of more humane treatment of offenders in a predominantly retributive system’ (Williams, 2005: 60). This controversial point leads us to another aspect of the debate around restorative justice, namely the extent to which this model of justice is victim-led or offender-led. It is the task of abolitionists to supersede this distinction. 12 Making Amends One of the controversies surrounding restorative justice centres on the reluctance of victims to participate in schemes which they suspect are geared to the interests of other parties rather than their own. Once they realise that an offender-approach is predominant, they comfortably return to the view that the only agency able to deal with offenders is the police force. Abolitionists outflank this controversy by embracing a different informal justice philosophy and practice. For Hulsman (1982), for example, the offender-victim dichotomy should be superseded by a view of crime as ‘natural disaster’, namely an event that requires solidarity mobilisation for those affected and efforts to prevent similar events from reoccurring. Natural disasters, though in a smaller scale, are likened to ‘trouble’, defined as situations in which people do not share a sense of how life is and should be structured, and where the lack of common perceptions results in conflict over ways of thinking, feeling and acting (Pfohl, 1981). In order to minimise conflicts, individuals may attempt to prevent trouble, through ‘rituals of primary ordering’, thus thwarting events which deviate from the order they see governing their lives. Or they can enact ‘rituals of reordering’, when they manage to cope with trouble and come to terms with the fact that conflicts are part of life (Hulsman, 1986). The controversy about offender-led or victim-led restorative justice is also examined against the background of other considerations. For example, it is stressed that some ‘alternative’ justice practices extend rather than reduce the prevailing justice system. In an overview offered by Shonholtz (1986) an echo is found of abolitionist critique of professionalism: agency-mediation implies specific 13 institutional actors such as prosecutors or the police applying specific mediation programmes and procedures. This model is built around the power and interests of institutional agencies: case referrals are generally coerced, while disputant participation is often involuntary. In other words, the parties would not attend the mediation session without the agency’s pressure. ‘Since most, if not all, of these referrals represent matters that the justice agency would not pursue formally, the agency-mediation programme presents the classic “widening the net” phenomenon so often criticised by criminologists’ (ibid: 229). In brief, agency-mediation programmes are promoted not because they handle criminal referrals, but precisely because those referrals are not seen as legitimate criminal cases. Such programmes represent a direct extension of the justice system into the non-criminal, or civil, arenas, and stem from the recognition that traditional sources of social control (the family, the church, the neighbourhood) are declining: the state enters non-state areas. ‘There is no attempt by the state to improve the ability or capacity of communities to manage their own conflicts through non-state mechanisms…. Thus the intention of agency-mediation programmes is to provide another layer of state-sponsored social control beyond the direct application of traditional justice theory or practice’ (ibid: 230). On the contrary, mediation promoted by community boards, as advocated by abolitionists, follows a voluntary referral model and is characterised by a community- centred rationale. The model urges the commitment of social resources and the revival of collective responsibility. It aims less at the suppression of conflict than at its early expression and potential resolution. It links the justice process to community forums 14 led by the residents’ need to organise local conflict-resolution mechanisms. It sees the development and maintenance of community justice forums as a democratic right and responsibility of citizens. Moreover, this model relies on residents trained in value- building, communication, and conciliation skills; panel sessions are open so that all are given the opportunity to develop such skills. Although institutional (or agency) mediation may help dilute the crime control system and act as a stimulant to local neighbourhoods, in the abolitionist perspective it may also lead to unwanted developments. For example, it may paradoxically revitalise the penal system, turning into ‘swift punishment without formalities’. It may increase control through the incorporation of a treatment ideology: punishment ends up becoming acceptable when disguised behind the notion of treatment (Christie, 1996). Or simply, it may weaken social competence, transferring problems to official actors. Individuals are de-skilled and made dependent upon external, state-funded or state-licensed entities. This brings to light another moot point within the restorative justice debate. Most programmes controlled by the state are regarded as suitable for co-option into the criminal justice status quo, with the community concerned taking on a subservient role. State intervention exacerbates the role of institutions as dumping ground for ‘people suffering from a wide range of human miseries’, it transfers to professionals the community ownership of miseries and problems (McKnight, 1995). In this way, ‘the criminal justice system compensates for the failings of economic, political, or social systems, which consequently deters the reform of these systems by removing people from open society who are its products’ (Elliott, 2009: 156). The community, thus, becomes an amorphous ideal, an acquiescent aggregation of citizens perfectly aligned with state agencies (Pavlich, 2005). Restorative justice focused on 15 community development, instead, ‘is less concerned with meeting the needs of institutions than it is with meeting the needs of the people involved in, and affected by, conflicts’ (Elliott, 2009: 164). Conflicts, therefore, should be seen as opportunities for establishing dialogue and seeking solutions, in a process leading to wider relationships and wider mutual knowledge. By placing the conflict within the skills and competency of trained community people, many of whom former disputants, mediation enacted by community forums or boards is able to place responsibility for the expression and resolution of the conflict on the disputants. ‘Moreover, the forum is the community’s statement of its capacity and confidence to accept responsibility for handling conflicts at the neighbourhood level. The voluntary resolution of conflict between disputants is advanced as a positive value… Voluntary resolutions are, first and foremost, a positive statement between the disputants about themselves, each other, and the situation’ (Shonholtz, 1986: 233-4). Shaming and Peace When abolitionists support voluntary resolution of conflict, they implicitly distance themselves from to the logic of reintegrative shaming, an ambivalent notion that raises enthusiasm and criticism in equal measure. According to Braithwaite (1989), shaming is more effective than conventional punishment in that it is not administered by a specific agency or institution, but involves the participation of a whole community. For the conscience-building effects of shaming to be produced, in fact, community-wide mobilisation is necessary. Children may learn about the evil of 16 murder and theft in an abstract manner, ‘but the shaming of the local offender known personally to children in the neighbourhood is especially important, because the wrongdoing and the shaming are so vivid as to have a lasting impression’ (ibid: 77). Regarded as akin to Etzioni’s (2001) communitarianism, this position has been the target of criticism for its implying a ‘monochrome society’ in which people identify one another with what they have in common rather than with what divides them. In such a society the loss of shared social and legal boundaries amounts to the decline of the policing force expressed by shame (Massaro, 1997). The revival of shaming punishment ‘as a way of expressing and reinforcing shared moral values’ is therefore recommended (Nussbaum, 2004: 175). Like the branding of the criminals in previous epochs, the shaming of offenders might take the form of a sign worn on their property, clothes or face. ‘I am a thief’ printed on a teenager’s T-shirt could be one example of shaming, although its integrative function remains to be proven. There are, however, different ways of applying the concept of communitarianism to criminal justice issues. In a theory of social order expressed by Cordella (1996), for example, conformity is determined by three distinct ‘unity patterns’ related to as many types of operational moralities. An ‘atomistic unity pattern’ guides individualism and opportunistic calculus, whereby those who conform do so for fear of retaliation. An ‘organic unity pattern’, which echoes Durkheimian categories, is enacted when individuals develop feelings of reciprocity due to the role and social rewards they enjoy in relation to similarly satisfied individuals. Finally, a ‘personal unity pattern’, which results from disinterested care for others and is engendered ‘by a common life and personal morality that is conciliatory with social harmony the primary goals’ (Richards, 2009: 115). While one may concur that the prevailing pattern in contemporary societies is the ‘atomistic unity pattern’, disagreement arises 17 as to the tools which may favour a shift from this to the other patterns. Can institutional shaming contribute to such shift, or is communitarian shaming better equipped for the task? The evangelical enthusiasm with which shaming in general has been received prompts a qualifying distinction. We have reintegrative shaming and disintegrative shaming or stigmatisation. The former expresses collective disapproval, which may range from ‘mild rebuke to degradation ceremonies’ followed by ‘gestures of reacceptance into the community of law-abiding citizens’. The deviant is thus decertified or de-labelled. In contrast, disintegrative shaming divides the community by creating a class of outcasts, whose only source of respect will be other similarly ‘shamed’ individuals and groups. ‘Much effort is directed at labelling deviance, while little attention is paid to de-labelling, to signifying forgiveness and reintegration, to ensuring that the deviance label is applied to the behaviour rather than the person, and that this is done under the assumption that the disapproved behaviour is transient, performed by an essentially good person’ (Braithwaite, 1989: 55). There is no space for either integrative or disintegrative shaming in abolitionist analysis. Integration, rather, is achieved through communal means with the involvement of actors who are devoid of the power to shame and do not supinely lend themselves to be shamed. For example, in his support of community boards, Hulsman (1982) stresses the importance of the training of local residents in conflict resolution. Local mediators, in his view, should listen to the parties separately, and prepare a resolution of compromise on the basis of what they have heard. This is then submitted 18 to those concerned in the conflict and amended until it is eventually accepted by all. Mediators, or conciliators, according to this model, are not required to resolve conflicts, rather, they are trained to help people acknowledge by themselves the nature of their conflicts, learn to listen to and understand one another. Community boards have also a hidden merit: because any given person should not be allowed to sit on one such board for longer than two years, slowly the situation will be reached where most local residents have been mediators or conciliators. With time, the whole community will become more ‘conciliatory’. Conclusion It is hard to establish to what extent abolitionist ideas have contributed to the increasing interest in non-penal measures. The timid and desultory processes of decarceration and decriminalisation that we have witnessed over the last decades may include abolitionist elements, particularly when accompanied by non institutional mediation, direct discussion between parties, and restitution or reparation of the damage caused. This, according to Christie (1986b: 104), may have reduced the state monopoly in inflicting pain, helped circulate ‘a set of ideas intended to reduce suffering, and increased positive responses and basic trust in ordinary human beings’. However, abolitionists share the view, recorded above, that non penal measures run the risk of being co-opted back by institutional actors; for example, mediation boards may become bureaucratised and ‘board-administrators might be temped to take on cases of shoplifting: they are mostly easy to handle and look good in the statistics’. Even compensation may turn into life-long debt for some offenders, while board members themselves may quite conventionally ‘share the common indignation when 19 children and young people misbehave’. Moreover, some offenders may find compensation more daunting than a traditional suspended sentence. Finally, boards may be ‘under the Ministry of Justice, a ministry accustomed to thinking in categories of utility and efficiency’ (Christie, 1996:198). In this paper the view of abolitionists on restorative justice has been presented, and their emphasis on community, rather than agency, conflict resolution has been discussed. Some forms of restorative justice, in the abolitionist critique, may discourage voluntary or lay members from joining mediation or reparation boards, because they may be viewed as mere ministerial emanations aimed at turning the initial community-led motivation of members into a profession. Returning to Durkheim’s concerns highlighted at the beginning, abolitionists seem aware that non-penal measures based on reparation and compensation may instil respect for the rules of the market rather than for other human beings. This, however, happens when abolitionist elements become institutionalised in official professional set ups. In such cases, members of mediation boards are converted into civil servants. The danger of institutionalisation, therefore, may be averted if the principles of ‘industrialised justice’ (as Christie calls it) are rejected, and a peaceful reactivation of community dynamics is pursued through participation. This would imply a fourfold solidarity: ‘for the people being sentenced, for their victims, for the community as a whole, and for those who guarantee the functioning of the penal system, who would feel happily liberated if they could stop working for the survival of such a machinery’ (Hulsman, 1986: 123). Durkheim’s observation that restitution ‘is not true solidarity’, because it restores relationships between individuals and things rather than between individuals, certainly applies to the model of ‘industrialised justice’, where organic solidarity is based on abstract division of labour, distance between roles and 20 anonymity of crowds. Professionalism exacerbates all of this, hampering the development of mutual dependence among individuals, whose experience of conflict is translated into agency routine. Response to crime, all too often, remains the remit of ‘experts in conflict’ rather than the arena for discussion among those experiencing it. Experts, inevitably, feel that they have to bring salvation and that their profession consists of a ‘fight’; consequently they may be led to acquire skills suitable for ‘humanitarian wars’. By contrast, We should turn to experts on how to create peace. For criminologists in particular, peace researchers are probably some of the most valuable potential models, providing categories, methods, insights and organisational principles of great relevance’ (Christie, 1986c: 53). References Bianchi, H. (1984), ‘L’imagination prisonnière. L’agonie romantique de Gianbattista Piranesi: une des clefs pour mieux comprendre le surgissement de la Grande Incarcération’, Déviance et Société, VIII : 225-231. Bianchi, H. (1986), ‘Abolition: Assensus and Sanctuary’, in Bianchi, H. and van Swaaningen, R. (eds), Abolitionism: Towards a Non-Repressive Approach to Crime, Amsterdam: Free University Press. Bianchi, H. (1991), ‘Abolitionism in the Past, Present and Future’, in Lasocik, Z., Platek, M. and Rzeplinska, I. (eds), Abolitionism in History: On Another Way of Thinking, Warsaw: Institute of Social Prevention and Resocialisation, University of Warsaw. Bianchi, H. (1994), Justice as Sanctuary: Toward a New System of Crime Control, Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press. Braithwaite, J. (1989), Crime, Shame and Reintegration, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Braithwaite, J. (2007), ‘Encourage Restorative Justice’, Criminology & Public Policy, 6 (4): 689-696. 21 Carlen, P. (1996), Jigsaw: A Political Criminology of Youth Homelessness, Buckingham: Open University Press. Casey, C. (1999), ‘Restoring the Faith’, Policing Today, March: 36-38. Christie, N. (1977), ‘Conflicts as Property’, The British Journal of Criminology, 17: 1-15. Christie, N. (1982), Limits to Pain, Oxford: Martin Robertson. Christie, N. (1986a), ‘Crime Control as Drama’, Journal of Law and Society, 13 (1): 1-8. Christie, N. (1986b), ‘Images of Man in Modern Penal Law’, Contemporary Crises, 10 (1): 95-106. Christie, N. (1986c), ‘Suitable Enemies’, in Bianchi, H. and van Swaaningen, R. (eds), Abolitionism: Towards a Non-Repressive Approach to Crime, Amsterdam: Free University Press. Christie, N. (1993), Crime Control as Industry: Towards Gulags, Western Style?, London: Routledge. Christie, N. (1996), ‘The Global Village, The Australian and New Zealand Journal of Criminology, 29: 195-199. Christie, N. (2004), A Suitable Amount of Crime, London and New York: Routledge. Durkheim, E. (1960), The Division of Labour in Society, Glencoe: The Free Press. Elliott, L. (2009), ‘A Geometry of Its Own: Restorative Justice, Relationships and Community in Democracy, in Ross, J.I. (ed), Cutting the Edge: Current Perspectives in Radical/Critical Criminology and Criminal Justice (Second Edition), Brunswick: Transaction. Etzioni, A. (2001), The Monochrome Society, Princeton: Princeton University Press. Hulsman, L. (1982), Peines perdues: le système pénal en question, Paris: Le Centurion (interview with J. Bernat de Célis). Hulsman, L. (1986), ‘Critical Criminology and the Concept of Crime’, Contemporary Crises, 10 (1): 63-80. Hulsman, L. (1991), ‘Alternatives to Criminal Justice: Decriminalization and Depenalization’, in Lasocik, Z., Platek, M. and Rzeplinska, I. (eds), Abolitionism in History: On Another Way of Thinking, Warsaw: Institute of Social Prevention and Resocialization. 22 Marshall, T. (1996), ‘The Evolution of Restorative Justice in Britain’, European Journal of Criminal Policy and Research, 4 (4): 21-43. Massaro, T. (1997), ‘Shame, Culture and American Criminal Law’, Michigan Law Review, 89: 1880-1942. Mathiesen, T. (1974), The Politics of Abolition: Essays in Political Action Theory, London: Martin Robertson. Mathiesen, T. (1990), Prison on Trial, London: Sage. Mathiesen, T. (2008), ‘The Abolitionist Stance’, plenary paper at the XII International Conference on Penal Abolition, Kings College, London, 23 July. McKnight, J. (1995), The Careless Society: Community and its Counterfeits, New York: Basic Books. McLaughlin, E., Fergusson, R., Hughes, G. and Westmarland, L. (eds) (2003), Restorative Justice: Critical Issues, London: Sage. Nader, L. and Todd, H.F. (eds) (1978), The Disputing Process: Law in Ten Societies, New York: Columbia University Press. Nussbaum, M. (2004), Hiding from Humanity: Disgust, Shame, and the Law, Princeton and Oxford: Princeton University Press. Pavlich, G. (2005), Governing Paradoxes of Restorative Justice, Portland: Glass House Press. Pfhol, S.J. (1981), ‘Labelling Criminals’, in Ross, H.L. (ed), Law and Deviance, Beverly Hills: Sage. Pollard, C. (2000), ‘Victims and the Criminal Justice System: A New Vision’, Criminal Law Review, 46: 5-17. Rock, P. (2004), Constructing Victims’ Rights: The Home Office, New Labour and Victims, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Ruggiero, V. (2010), Penal Abolitionism, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Shonholtz, R. (1986), ‘New Justice Theories and Practice’, in Bianchi, H. and van Swaaningen, R. (eds), Abolitionism: Towards a Non-Repressive Approach to Crime, Amsterdam: Free University Press. Simmel, G. (1950), The Sociology of Georg Simmel, New York: The Free Press. Strang, H. (2002), Repair or Revenge: Victims and Restorative Justice, Oxford: Oxford University Press. 23 Williams, B. (2005), Victims of Crime and Community Justice, London and Philadelphia: Jessica Kingsley. Wright, M. (2008), Making Good: Prisons, Punishment and Beyond (Second Edition), Hampshire: Waterside Press. work_6yaothgfyvexdp5dlw773h6zem ---- S P E C I A L P A P E R DOI: dx.doi.org/10.5195/jmla.2019.712 jmla.mlanet.org 107 (3) July 2019 Journal of the Medical Library Association 291 Social justice and the medical librarian* Elaine Russo Martin, FMLA See end of article for author’s affiliation. This lecture discusses social justice and the role that medical librarians can play in a democratic society. Social justice needs to be central to the mission of medical librarianship and a core value of the profession. Medical librarians must develop a new professional orientation: one that focuses on cultural awareness or cultural consciousness that goes beyond ourselves and our collections to that which focuses on the users of our libraries. We must develop a commitment to addressing the issues of societal, relevant health information. Using examples from medical education, this lecture makes the case for social justice librarianship. This lecture also presents a pathway for social justice medical librarianship, identifies fundamental roles and activities in these areas, and offers strategies for individual librarians, the Medical Library Association, and library schools for developing social justice education and outcomes. The lecture advocates for an understanding of and connection to social justice responsibilities for the medical library profession and ends with a call to go beyond understanding to action. The lecture emphasizes the lack of diversity in our profession and the importance of diversity and inclusion for achieving social justice. The lecture presents specific examples from some medical libraries to extend the social justice mindset and to direct outreach, collections, archives, and special collection services to expose previously hidden voices. If medical librarians are to remain relevant in the future, we must act to address the lack of diversity in our profession and use our information resources, spaces, and expertise to solve the relevant societal issues of today. INTRODUCTION I am truly honored to have been selected as the 2018 Janet Doe lecturer. Like the many Doe lecturers before me, being selected brings a host of mixed emotions, varying from amazement, joy, pleasure, and ultimately panic from the weight of the responsibility. The Janet Doe Lecture is an extensive examination of a topic related to health sciences librarianship. The topic is open ended, as long as the subject is under the very broad theme of philosophy or history. Like most of the Doe lecturers before me, I too am not a philosopher nor a historian. My career as a medical librarian has been a journey both literally and figuratively. I have worked on both coasts and in the middle of the country, deliberately relocating to accept more advanced leadership positions. I have outreach experience in three Regional Medical Library network offices: the Pacific Northwest, the Greater Midwest Region, and the New England * The Janet Doe Lecture on the history or philosophy of medical librarianship, presented at MLA ’18, the 118th Annual Meeting Medical Library Association, Inc.; Atlanta, GA; May 18–23, 2018. Julia Sollenberger, AHIP, FMLA, the 2017 Janet Doe lecturer, gave the introduction. Region (in these last two, I led those programs). A defining moment in my career was the opportunity I had to work outside the United States, specifically in Liberia. I started my library career as a library technician in a state medical society library and continued working in different support staff positions while attending library school part-time with the support of the Medical Library Association (MLA) Scholarship. My first professional job out of library school was as a reference/user education librarian, followed by administrative positions as a public services department head, an assistant director, then an associate director, and finally, a library director. The libraries in which I worked were in both private and public academic health sciences centers with a variety of health professional schools and affiliated hospitals. Because of this breadth of experience, the kinds of projects I have worked on, and the diversity of the communities in which I have worked, the 2 9 2 R u s s o M a r t i n DOI: dx.doi.org/10.5195/jmla.2019.712 Journal of the Medical Library Association 107 (3) July 2019 jmla.mlanet.org topic for this lecture came naturally to me. I did not, like many previous Doe lecturers, experience a long and agonizing road for a search for my topic. For me, it was quite the opposite. In fact, the topic chose me and seemed a natural fit. I fleetingly thought about and quickly dismissed discussing the work I have done and continue to do in promoting research data management as a fundamental new role for medical librarians or my project in public health information access and outreach, specifically my approach to providing real- time access to the literature for the public health workforce who have no affiliation with academic medical libraries. But I must confess my choice of topic comes from contemporary concerns about what is going on in our society today and is influenced by movements such as #BlackLivesMatter, #Metoo, #Enough, #Resistance, #NeverAgain, and #MarchforOurLives, and the proliferation of accepted terms such as “fake news” or “alternative facts.” When I started exploring social justice as my topic, I had some initial doubts as to whether or not I should go forward. I acknowledge that some librarians might feel uncomfortable with the topic and what is to follow. However, given what has gone on to threaten our country’s democratic values and principles, I am more convinced than ever that I had to discuss “Social Justice and the Medical Librarian.” I think most of us would agree that democracy in any country depends on an informed electorate with equal access to quality information, knowledge, and education. Therefore, by definition, the library profession is an integral part of democracy. Specifically, what we medical librarians do—making evidence-based health information available to those who need it in order to help patients, families, and caregivers make better patient-care decisions— connects us to democratic principles and ideals of equal access to information and health care. As Louis Brandeis, a former Supreme Court associate justice and “militant crusader for social justice,” asked and answered, “What are American ideals? They are the development of the individual for his own good and the common good; the development of the individual through liberty; and the attainment of the common good though democracy and social justice” [1]. In the United States, we have the means for such democratic ideals, but we have not lived up to the potential [2]. American democracy is in danger because of an increasingly ill-informed public who are easily manipulated with sound bites and Twitter rants that lead to the infringement on the rights of the poor, the disenfranchised, the underserved, immigrants, people of color, women, and the lesbian, gay, bisexual, trans, and queer (LGBTQ) community. With the continuing closures of hospital libraries and relentless budget cuts experienced by many academic medical libraries since 2008, coupled with the proliferation of many alternative options for accessing information, the need for medical librarians is being questioned, and our sheer numbers, ranks, and status are diminishing. If medical librarians are to survive as a distinct profession, then we must consider who we are as individuals, embrace our place as medical professionals in a democratic society, stand up for human rights and social justice, and assert our social responsibility. Few Doe lecturers have touched upon the roles of medical librarians in a democratic society. Henry Lemkau Jr., FMLA, in his 2007 Doe lecture, said, “Our lives are informed and given purpose by the influences that surround us,” and he discussed our profession “in the context of the social and cultural worlds in which we function” [3]. I suggest that this discussion has never been more important than it is today, given the times in which we live (mass deportations, children separated from their families at the border, no sustained solution for the Dreamers, and a government shutdown over the border wall). I would add to the discussion the context of the users, not just the professions, whom we serve. The importance of human values in medical librarianship was first highlighted by Martha Jane Zachert in her 1978 Doe lecture [4]. Previous to her, Doe lecturers defined the values of medical librarianship in terms of collection-building, self- image, organization and retrieval methods, and technological savvy. David Bishop’s definition of diversity, for example, only focused on specialization in the field of librarianship and did not touch on diversity with respect to populations [5]. But it was Zachert who wrote of developing new values for the medical library profession “related to man’s cognitive life and social, as well as to social and cultural institutions and the process of social change.” She identified professionalism as one of our most “enduring values...perhaps the keynote of our value system” [4]. In my view, professionalism goes beyond the tasks we do or what we call S o c i a l j u s t i c e a n d t h e m e d i c a l l i b r a r i a n 2 9 3 DOI: dx.doi.org/10.5195/jmla.2019.712 jmla.mlanet.org 107 (3) July 2019 Journal of the Medical Library Association ourselves, but rather embodies who we are and what we stand for [5]. For the most part, Doe lecturers have shied away from discussing politics and its effect on their topics or the medical library profession. Estelle Brodman was an exception with a somewhat lengthy discussion of the effect of Hitler’s Nazis, the Vietnam War, racism, and the perils of the “pursuit of power” over the “pursuit of excellence” [6]. The 1989 Doe lecture by Rachael K. Anderson, AHIP, FMLA, was the first to explore the factors that have influenced who has been able to enter our profession, with a particular focus on racial and gender discrimination [7]. Gerald Oppenheimer, in 1988, was most adamant about our profession looking outward and “concentrating on values…which are directed outward to the society in which we live and work” [8]. He went on to describe the debate in MLA between those who felt we should leave human rights to others and those who felt the association should take a more active role in democratic ideals. You may think given the title of my talk that it is also a political talk. Promoting equality and democratic ideals is not partisan. Rather, it is a talk about values and what Barack Obama named democracy with a small “d” [9]. It is a talk about social justice in our everyday work. It is a talk about how we can be relevant to the people we serve by providing information that improves everyone’s health, not just the privileged few. It is a talk about professionalism, and how we can incorporate and promote social justice into our profession, how we can become agents of societal change, and how we practice as medical librarians in the context of the times in which we live. DEFINING SOCIAL JUSTICE —Of all the forms of inequality, injustice in health care is the most shocking and inhumane. Martin Luther King [10] What do I mean then by social justice in the context of health care and medicine? While social justice and diversity are linked, social justice goes beyond representation. A term hard to define, social justice in medicine is: the open acknowledgement of the dignity and autonomy of and delivery of high-quality medical care, to all members of society, regardless of gender, race, ethnicity, religion, sexual orientation, language, geography, origin, or socioeconomic background. [11] It is the idea that health care employees work toward eliminating racial and ethnic disparities in health care [11]. The 2002 Institute of Medicine report, Unequal Treatment, first detailed a systematic examination of racial and ethnic disparities in health care. It clearly indicated that US racial and ethnic minorities were less likely to receive even routine medical procedures and more likely to experience a lower quality of health services, and called out the social responsibility of physicians toward their patients [12]. Social justice is not just an admirable idea. Social justice is a responsibility of the health care team to provide health services for every person, no matter where they live, what they do, or what lifestyles they lead. The case for social justice medical librarianship comes from our roots in the health professions and medical education. I hope this talk challenges our preconceived notions of the role librarians should play in social justice and suggests some specific actions. There is a growing recognition amongst the health professions and medical educators that there is disparity in the health care delivered to ethnic, racial, gender, and other minority populations [13]. These disparities lead to patient dissatisfaction, noncompliance with treatment, and poorer health outcomes. Diseases such as tuberculosis and HIV are social diseases. There is recognition that the impact of societal and economic factors on the individual needs to be considered just as much as the bacteria of the disease itself [14]. There needs to be a broader awareness of the barriers to accessing health services among underrepresented groups. There also needs to be a comprehensive strategy in addressing them [12]. The Liaison Committee on Medical Education (LCME) standard 7.6 is one concrete step [15]. All medical schools in the United States and Canada must address the issues of social justice, cultural competency, diversity, and inclusion along with the need for medical students “to recognize and appropriately address gender and cultural biases in health care delivery” as part of the medical school accreditation process. Specifically, medical students must demonstrate an understanding of how culturally diverse perspectives of health and illness affect a person’s response to symptoms, disease, and 2 9 4 R u s s o M a r t i n DOI: dx.doi.org/10.5195/jmla.2019.712 Journal of the Medical Library Association 107 (3) July 2019 jmla.mlanet.org treatment. The LCME standards also require students to understand how gender and cultural biases affect health care delivery [16]. Medical education is not alone: these themes are reflected in transforming the education of future nurses, public health workers, and other members of the health care team. If medical librarians are to maintain our status as members of the health professional team, then we, too, must take up the call. I would even go so far to say that future survival as a profession depends on it. Rudolf Virchow, who is considered the father of social medicine, wrote in 1848, “Medicine is a social science, and politics nothing but medicine on a grand scale” [17]. Despite this, just like medical librarianship, the medical profession has been slow to respond to society’s issues. The medical professions’ late response to the HIV/AIDS pandemic and its effect on the LGBTQ community is only one example. Yet as evidenced by the LCME accreditation standards and the increased number of journal articles in Academic Medicine over the last decade, there seems to be a greater awareness among medical educators that teaching social justice to medical trainees and medical school faculty needs to be essential to educating future health professionals. SOCIAL JUSTICE AND MEDICAL SCHOOL CURRICULUM There are examples of medical schools incorporating social justice into their curricular offerings: • Through problem-based learning methods, medical students and faculty at the University of Hawaii have developed the Social Justice Curriculum Project, consisting of self-directed learning, action, and self-reflection [18]. • The University of California Davis Health System offers faculty development training on how to conduct interracial dialogue on race, racism, oppression, and privilege [19]. • In memory of Freddie Gray, faculty at Northeastern Ohio University have designed a curriculum to help trainees and faculty understand unequal access to health care and how physicians can work toward eliminating the injustices contributing to inappropriate care [20]. • The Human Rights and Social Justice Scholars Program at the Icahn School of Medicine at Mount Sinai is a preclinical training program in social medicine that incorporates service learning experiences with lectures, mentorship, research projects, policy and advocacy projects, and a seminar series [18, 21]. • The Harvard Medical School hosts the “Equity and Social Justice” series of lectures and dialogues focusing on history and context, culture and environment, health disparities, and leadership and skills development. Other medical schools are going beyond the LCME guidelines and are beginning to also provide advocacy training to address social determinants of health. The LEADS Curriculum at the University of Colorado School of Medicine, the Scholarly Concentration in Advocacy and Activism at the Brown University Warren Alpert Medical School, and the Health Justice Scholar Track at Georgetown University School of Medicine are early examples that focus on empowering medical students to design and execute advocacy projects for social change. I am fully aware of the criticisms of social justice and social justice education. Some may think it too politically liberal, or too politically correct, or too leftist or activist. Some may feel that they cannot express their conservative views in these settings. The goal of social justice is not to have us conform to one way of thinking but rather to give everyone the opportunity to be engaged, thoughtful community members who think critically about issues affecting the community. This is the tradition of a liberal education without having politically liberal connotations. It is where students, educators, and librarians recognize the complexity of the world and our interconnectedness. It is an opportunity for us all to reflect and think critically about these issues, develop tolerance for ambiguity, appreciate diversity, and respect the different views of others [22]. THE CASE FOR SOCIAL JUSTICE AND THE MEDICAL LIBRARIAN Like medicine, medical librarianship is not only an information science, but a human science. It is the search, retrieval, evaluation, and application of information to meet human needs to help health professionals, students, and patients make informed decisions about their health. Currently, much of what we do in medical libraries still focuses on developing vast libraries of print or online collections, enhancing informatics technology-based S o c i a l j u s t i c e a n d t h e m e d i c a l l i b r a r i a n 2 9 5 DOI: dx.doi.org/10.5195/jmla.2019.712 jmla.mlanet.org 107 (3) July 2019 Journal of the Medical Library Association skills, and developing evidence-based best practices for delivering reference, education, or other services. While performing activities such as developing data science plans, digitizing special collections, and conducting systematic reviews are important, they need to be done in a social justice context. Through a social justice lens, we would need to introduce more humanistic approaches to our work: refocusing our attention from serving ourselves and what is more efficient or effective for us to do in our libraries and shifting our focus outward. We need to focus on learning what our users want from us, learning how individual users experience the library, and tailoring our services and approach to their individual needs and experience. Social justice librarianship involves developing a personal and professional approach in which the practice of medical librarianship puts the user’s interests and needs front and center. Like medicine, we have been slow to recognize what our social responsibility to those we serve is and that there is no one size fits all to the services we provide. This lecture critically discusses this concept of social justice and proposes that medical librarians must go beyond the traditional approaches to thinking about their work and must develop a deeper understanding of and connection with the social responsibilities of the health professions and people we serve. Medical librarians must develop a new professional orientation—one that fosters a critical awareness or critical consciousness of going beyond the self to others and a commitment to addressing the issues of societal relevant health information. This new professional orientation or identity places information science in a social and cultural context. It is coupled with a recognition of societal injustices with respect to access to health care and health information and a search for appropriate action. I will suggest a framework for medical librarianship social justice, identify the fundamental roles and activities in these areas, and suggest strategies for individual librarians as well as MLA, the Association of Academic Health Sciences Libraries (AAHSL), and schools of library and information sciences (LIS) for developing education and outcomes. It is my hope that, through this lecture, you will gain an understanding of and connection to the social responsibilities of medical librarianship, develop an individual approach to reflective professional practice, and be inspired to action. THE SOCIAL JUSTICE EDUCATION DEBATE While there is more agreement today that health professionals need to be trained in cultural competence, multiculturalism, and social justice, there is a debate regarding the curriculum and the accompanying teaching methods. In academic medicine, proponents of critical consciousness theory view it as a way to help refocus the current methods of health professional education. Medical education focuses on developing procedurally competent physicians. Adding social justice to health education brings physician training back to its original mission of developing socially conscious health providers who focus on the patient-doctor relationship and to “inform an appropriate crucial pedagogy for fostering compassionate, humanistic, socially conscious health professionals who act as agents of change” [23]. The early efforts in social justice medical education curricula stress developing competencies in multiculturalism. These efforts use the categorical approach where attitudes, beliefs, and behaviors of specific cultures and groups are defined, outlined, taught, and memorized. While acquiring multicultural competence implies learning about multiple and diverse cultures, it is limiting. It often leads to oversimplifying and stereotyping certain groups. This is an unintended outcome. This realization has led to new teaching methodologies that focus on developing a set of skills to assess individually what factors might affect a patient’s care or developing critical consciousness [11]. Medical educator Delese Wear cautions that it is not enough to be culturally competent and, in fact, multicultural competency–based education can become “a medical education paradigm in which the notion of ‘novelty’ replaces that of ‘equality’ in approaches to treating patients” [20]. Kumagai argues that a competency-based approach to social justice education is not appropriate, as linear modes of learning may help the student accumulate knowledge but not necessarily understanding. He argues for new ways of thinking about how students learn or know. Teaching social justice to support professionalism calls for new content and new teaching methods [24]. 2 9 6 R u s s o M a r t i n DOI: dx.doi.org/10.5195/jmla.2019.712 Journal of the Medical Library Association 107 (3) July 2019 jmla.mlanet.org The concept of the medical professional who practices actively in the world involves a paradigm shift away from passive learning of new knowledge and skills to more active learning. It requires developing a new professional identity with a reflective orientation to the understanding of self, professional self, others, and the world. It has its roots in “Critical Conscious Theory,” a term proposed by Brazilian activist and theorist Paulo Freire in his 1970 work, Pedagogy of the Oppressed. Critical consciousness goes beyond critical thinking. It is the “ability to intervene in reality in order to change it.” The link from education to democracy is implicit in Freire’s work. Learners act as subjects in the creation of democracy in education through telling and listening to experiences. Consciousness is a sense of one’s personal and collective identity, an in- depth understanding of the world, and a penchant for action against oppression [25]. Friere saw the act of dialogue as an act of proclaimed equality: dialogue, curiosity, creativity, and critical consciousness actively seek to intervene and change society. He observed the educational system in Brazil, which focused on spoon-feeding or banking and depositing knowledge to the masses, as oppressive. He advocated for more active learning and questioning as a way of freeing the individual. He felt that learners needed to connect to their own personal, cognitive, and emotional experience; to engage with others through dialogue; and to emancipate themselves and others through praxis (applying theory to action). This capacity to connect with one’s position in society and engage in dialogue about inequities depends upon critical consciousness—a reflective reading of the world. From consciousness, learners could act as agents of change. Social justice education is actively learning by doing. Friere’s theory of critical consciousness has been applied to educational change in various disciplines, most recently, medical education: A Friere critical teacher is a problem-poser who asks thought provoking questions and encourages students to ask their own questions…students experience education as something they do, not as something done to them…educators…are challenged to de-privilege their own power and authority and become informed, experienced and knowledgeable facilitators of student learning rather than depositors of information into the mental vaults of learners. [26] Students are both teachers and learners and vice versa. Kumagai expands on Friere’s work as applied to teaching social justice in a medical context. He calls on the teachings of German philosopher Jürgen Habermas and his framework for knowing and communicating. Teaching social justice requires another type of learning, by which individuals (and, indeed, groups and societies as a whole) formulate new ways of understanding reality, of interacting with others, and of perceiving their own identities. Habermas identifies three primary ways in which we generate knowledge. The first is “Work” or instrumental action—knowledge based upon empirical investigation and governed by technical rules. Scientific research is an example of this domain. In librarianship, this may equate to technical work in maintaining systems and collections. The second is “Practical Knowledge.” This domain identifies human social interaction or “Communicative Action.” It is defined by “building consensus or standards” in order to determine appropriate action. Legal and social sciences belong to the “Practical.” In medical librarianship, “Practical” is the way we help develop clinical practice. The last is “Emancipatory,” or “self- knowledge” or “Self-reflection.” This involves: interest in the way one’s history and biography has expressed itself in how one sees oneself, one’s roles and social expectations…Insights gained through critical self- awareness are emancipatory. Knowledge is gained by self- emancipation through reflection leading to a transformed consciousness or changed perspective. [27, 28] For medical librarians, this can include approaching the reference interview from the user’s perspective and having a greater awareness of our own biases prior to providing canned searches or information packets. The medical librarian needs to have empathy for the individual asking the reference question and treat every question as an individual need. Habermas’s framework of knowing is important to consider as we think about a social justice framework for medical librarianship. Although medical training, appropriately so, must focus on developing technical skills and consensus-driven understanding of best clinical practice, not all education to prepare health professionals to work in society arises from these ways of knowing. Implicit in the efforts to introduce more humanistic care into medicine and to address S o c i a l j u s t i c e a n d t h e m e d i c a l l i b r a r i a n 2 9 7 DOI: dx.doi.org/10.5195/jmla.2019.712 jmla.mlanet.org 107 (3) July 2019 Journal of the Medical Library Association topics as social justice and human values into professional training is a requirement that a new way of knowing does not involve just knowing facts and figures. It involves the personal and professional orientation toward self and others—a way of being in the world—in which the practice of medicine has the patient’s interests at the forefront. This way of being cannot be taught through traditional lecture or classroom settings but must be acquired through reflection, dialogue, and experience [28]. This type of education engages learners and teachers in the exploration of self and others through the use of narratives, reflective writings, comics, art, theater, and film. The emphasis is to engage in reflective interaction with a play, film, or essay; with a patient; and with each other in opportunities to grapple with moments of uncertainty and discomfort, and to go ultimately beyond discussion to action in the world. Medical libraries, schools of LIS, and our medical library associations need to emulate the efforts from our health professional colleagues when it comes to social justice education. We need to introduce more of these ways of learning and concepts into our formal and informal curriculum for medical librarians. DIVERSITY IN LIBRARIANSHIP Let me now turn to diversity in our profession. Though not the same as social justice, diversity is important for achieving it. While the library community considers diversity to be a core value, the library sector has fallen short, despite ongoing initiatives that focus on the recruiting minority librarians. What do we mean when we say diversity, and why does diversity matter? Diversity matters because we want our libraries to be reflective of the diverse communities in which we work and the users we serve. A recent McKinsey analysis of 366 global public companies found that those companies with greater ethnic diversity are 35% more likely to outperform their peers: “Diversity matters because it is an opportunity to be innovative, to leverage gifts and talents of all our people” [29]. For at least the last two decades, many academic libraries have established diversity committees, residency programs, and fellowship opportunities for minorities in order to increase representation in the workforce. In recent years, some academic librarians have worked toward understanding this issue and have spoken out about the shortcomings of efforts to diversify the profession and advocate for social justice [30]. Professional associations have grappled with the issue of diversity and initiated efforts to increase the representative numbers of library employees of color in librarianship. Library organizations have implemented programs toward effecting change in the racial and ethnic makeup of the profession. In 1997, the American Library Association (ALA) began the Spectrum Scholarship Program meant to address ethnic under- representation in the library community. More recently, the Association of Research Libraries began providing a number of diversity initiatives surrounding recruitment and career development of underrepresented ethnic groups, including the “Initiative to Recruit a Diverse Workforce” and the “Leadership and Early Career Development Program,” among others. The Association of College and Research Libraries has in recent years formed a Diversity Alliance. MLA has had a Scholarship for Minority Students and recently formed the Diversity and Inclusion Task Force; AAHSL has acted similarly. Despite these efforts, librarianship remains a primarily white female profession. The Ithaca S+R report, funded by the Andrew Mellon Foundation, called the “Inclusion, Diversity, and Equity Survey,” is the most recent attempt to measure representational diversity in libraries and documents the lack of racial and ethnic diversity in the profession. It found that over 75% of employees at academic research libraries were white. And as positions become increasingly senior, they also become increasingly white [31]. The report also found that library leaders or administrators are 89% white and non-Hispanic. It also noted that many non-white staff members work in roles such as technical services, processing, and so on, which are being phased out of libraries as they move from print to electronic collections. One of the study’s coauthors Roger Schonfeld wonders whether “There is in fact a risk that libraries will become not more diverse in the future but potentially less diverse in the future if action isn’t taken” [31]. The report gives credence to minority staff who have faced barriers to advancement. These issues become even more pronounced as the national population has grown markedly more diverse. The US population (2013 figures) is 62% 2 9 8 R u s s o M a r t i n DOI: dx.doi.org/10.5195/jmla.2019.712 Journal of the Medical Library Association 107 (3) July 2019 jmla.mlanet.org white, with a projection for 2060 that white people will make up only 40% of the population [32]. Using the ALA Diversity Counts data and comparing it to the US Census data for 2013 and US Census projections for 2060, it is clear that we are far from reflecting our country’s diversity. However, diversity has a much broader definition than race and ethnic representation and encompasses combatting discrimination based on age, sex, sexual orientation, gender identity, gender expression, religious background, language, or disability. The ALA Diversity Counts data go beyond highlighting the disparity for race and ethnicity. We lack other forms of diversity in libraries as well, though demographic data for areas other than race and ethnicity are less well defined or tracked. The Diversity Counts authors highlight the low employment of librarians with disabilities, given the increase between 1990 and 2000 of people self-identifying as having 1 or more disabilities. While 19% of 21–64 year olds self-identified as having a disability on the 2000 US Census, the percentage of credentialed librarians was 4% [32]. The recent Association of American Medical Colleges (AAMC) report called “Learners and Disabilities” is similarly discouraging. Only 2.5% of 1,500 medical students self-identified as having disabilities and needing accommodations [33]. The report highlights the barriers that medical students with disabilities experience in their training. Going back to librarians, the Diversity Counts report states, “Credentialed librarians are predominately women, ages 45–54, and white. They are not limited by disability and work full-time” [32, 34]. This lack of diversity in libraries in regard to race, ethnicity, disability, and other factors distance the very communities we seek to serve. And it suggests a proportionally less diverse library workforce on the horizon [34]. We need to ask ourselves why diversity does not happen despite libraries making diversity a priority. Why are these efforts not making any meaningful difference? Why are we bringing people from underrepresented groups into our libraries at the same rate they are leaving the profession [34]? What are the barriers to diversifying employees? When asked this question in the Ithaka survey, library directors recognize there is a problem but identify the problem as something they cannot control. They blame external factors, such as lack of a talent pool or geographical location, rather than internal factors such as unconscious bias in the interview process. [31]. In addition, they identify their libraries as more inclusive than the library community as a whole, whether or not that is the case [31]. Yet, we know that in comparing the percentage of racial and ethnic subgroups in the US population, the distribution in library assistant positions is more or less proportional, whereas the distribution in professional librarian positions is not, the latter skewing heavily to an overrepresentation of white people. Diversity Counts confirms this discrepancy [35]. One strategy may be to look internally for higher education and promotional opportunities for library assistants in our own libraries. Perhaps looking in our libraries and not outside the environment is where the problem really lies. When I was at the University of Illinois at Chicago, for example, the university librarian, Sharon Hogan, sponsored a program for underrepresented minority library assistants to attend the master’s of library and information science (MLIS) program at the University of Illinois Urbana-Champaign. Selected employees went to school on weekends (tuition free), the library provided transportation, and upon graduation, students/employees were guaranteed a paid professional position in the library system. It should be easier today to implement programs like this, especially since there are so many online LIS degree programs available. Eligible employees could be given educational leave to complete coursework, allowed to use work computers, and receive tuition benefits. Common library hiring processes and practices also contribute to the lack of diversity. We need to examine the criteria for job descriptions, recruitment processes, and hiring practices to open up the pipeline for underrepresented groups to enter the profession and provide opportunities for advancement. While we discuss and say we encourage the recruitment of library workers from diverse backgrounds, our application requirements are not designed to celebrate the experiences of diverse applicants. We need to reframe application requirements, materials, and interview questions in ways that make sense for a variety of applicants’ experiences [36]. S o c i a l j u s t i c e a n d t h e m e d i c a l l i b r a r i a n 2 9 9 DOI: dx.doi.org/10.5195/jmla.2019.712 jmla.mlanet.org 107 (3) July 2019 Journal of the Medical Library Association SOCIAL JUSTICE IN MEDICAL LIBRARIANSHIP In earlier portions of this talk, I discussed how medical educators and health professional students have incorporated social justice, through critical consciousness, into their work and studies. I have also discussed how our profession has been challenged in achieving success in diversity despite our efforts. Though social justice has not been the focal point for the medical library profession, there are examples in which individual medical librarians have been active in what I would call social justice outreach. One such example is the response of some of our members to the appearance of HIV/AIDS in the early 1980s, a disease that was social and stigmatized the populations it affected. While only a handful of articles about this new disease appeared in peer-reviewed journals in the early 1980s and the disease was never recognized until after the Ronald Reagan presidency, new and different sources of information were developing to fill the void. Gay and community-based organizations primarily in New York and San Francisco, where effects of the disease were most felt, were collecting and distributing information about treatment and prevention; often with the help of medical librarians working with these organizations. The first MLA presentation on this topic, “The AIDS Information Crisis: Confluence of the Roles of Information Creator, Seeker, and Provider,” by David Ginn, which was delivered at the 1987 annual meeting in Portland, Oregon, chronicled the information phenomenon in the gay and community-based organizations and called for the AIDS information gap to be addressed by our profession [37]. At the same time, M. Kent Mayfield, MLA headquarters continuing education program leader, enlisted Ginn and Richard Stevens, AIDS director of the Health Council of South Florida, to develop an AIDS information course outlining the new and expanding types of information that existed in the community setting. In the meantime, Gerald J. Perry, AHIP, FMLA, and Jeffrey T. Huber were publishing important books on AIDS information resources and terminology. Perry later went on to form the LGBT Health Sciences Librarians Special Interest Group (SIG) in MLA. In 1994, the National Library of Medicine (NLM) developed a special funding mechanism for HIV/AIDS community-based information access, in which some of us have partnered over the last twenty plus years, bringing information retrieval, skills development, computer acquisition, and Internet access to this affected community. There are numerous other projects funded by NLM in which medical librarians partnered with community-based organizations to enhance the health information literacy of underserved populations. As they are too numerous to name them all, I will highlight a few I am most familiar with. Projects included partnerships with mental health patients and providers. E-mental health programs, coordinated through the Countway Library with partners at the Massachusetts Department of Mental Health and the Dartmouth College and Harvard University Medical Schools, were designed to enhance the health information literacy of seriously ill mental health patients and their families, focusing on co-occurring disease. Persons with serious mental illness have high mortality rates, tend be smokers, experience obesity, and present with multiple physical health concerns. This project focused on information related to physical as well as mental health resources. Another project I worked on while in Worcester addressed the opioid crisis. We worked with the city’s first alternative high school for addicted teens. Medical librarians worked with students, their parents, and their teachers to create a resource room with Internet, computer, and pamphlet materials and sponsored speakers who focused on options for recovery, addiction counseling, and the decriminalization of addiction. When NLM broadened its attention to serving consumers in addition to health professionals, its funding for health information outreach to minorities, underserved, and vulnerable populations through the National Network of Libraries of Medicine (NNLM) has been and continues to be a critical vehicle for social justice librarianship. Medical librarians partnered with public libraries to provide consumer health collections and access to MedlinePlus, computers, and Internet connections as well as training for public librarians. In 2002, for example, medical librarians from the Yale University Harvey Cushing/John Hay Whitney Medical Library partnered with the New Haven Free Public Library to develop a Consumer Health Information Center with collection and information services for the city’s public library users who are traditionally from minority and economically disadvantaged groups. Then Library Director Regina Kenny 3 0 0 R u s s o M a r t i n DOI: dx.doi.org/10.5195/jmla.2019.712 Journal of the Medical Library Association 107 (3) July 2019 jmla.mlanet.org Marone received a recognition award from the city for her leadership in this project. Another example is the SPIRAL project from Tufts University Hirsch Health Sciences Library. SPIRAL stands for “Selected Patient Information Resources in Asian Languages.” Partnering with the Chinatown community in Boston, Tufts University health sciences librarians and community health center providers developed a free online website with patient health information resources in languages such as Chinese, Vietnamese, Cambodian, Korean, Thai, and Japanese. Medical librarians working in international librarianship in conjunction with health care providers to expand medical education curricular and accompanying library resources in countries such as Liberia speak to our profession’s commitment to improving health through equal access to information in a global society. The societal impacts of diseases such as Ebola on a country like Liberia are major, threatening the peace process, causing psychological distress, and resulting in numerous losses of life for the citizenry and health care providers, causing a breakdown of the health care and educational systems. Cultural considerations such as burial practices and wide distrust of traditional healers as well as a lack of basic infrastructure (regular electricity, limited Internet access) hindered efforts in the beginning to control the disease. In a country like Liberia, which was recovering from decades of civil war and whose people experienced years where educational institutions could not operate, basic library services such as print textbooks, a manual check-out system, and copy cataloging served the medical school faculty and students well. The Ebola outbreak resulted in the closing of the medical school, but post-outbreak that basic library was continuing to function when the medical school reopened, and luckily, all the staff we worked with survived the crises, though some of the students had died. The Countway Library of Medicine, Harvard Medical School, is extending the social justice mindset beyond direct outreach services to incorporating a public history perspective to its medical archives and special collections. The project uses a pubic history perspective to apply history to real-world problems. The project, “Equal Access: Stories of Diversity and Inclusion at Harvard Medical School,” focuses on collecting resources that fill in the gaps in the history of medical education. The project includes oral histories and papers from students and faculty who are underrepresented in medicine, including the first women and African American students and faculty. The intention is to use these collections to create a “dialogical” with collaboration and input from the community whose collections are being archived and personal stories recorded in order to more fully interpret and understand the issues surrounding barriers to accessing medical education and why this history is important. The success of these and similar projects depends not on just going into the community and making resources available. All these outreach projects involve getting to know the community and its cultures, developing an equal partnership with the community, showing respect for cultural norms and practices, and then tailoring services to these. Medical librarians’ obligation in providing consumer health information services to the public is a relatively recent phenomenon. MLA’s recognition of the Consumer and Patient Health Information Section, the subsequent Consumer Health Information Specialization, and most recent announcement of nominations for the newly endowed MLA Consumer Health Librarian of the Year Award have cemented what was once regarded as a controversial new role into accepted practice. CALL TO ACTION —A man dies when he refuses to stand up for that which is right. A man dies when he refuses to stand up for justice. A man dies when he refuses to take a stand for that which is true. Martin Luther King [38] If medical librarians are to remain relevant in the future, I believe we must deal with the lack of diversity in our profession, actively create our future using humanistic approaches, and use our information resources, spaces, and expertise to solve relevant issues of today. These include addressing the social and racial injustices in health care. We can use our library spaces to encourage critical consciousness conversations about the hard issues such as racism, sexism, gun violence, health disparities, climate change, and other societal issues affecting the health of the nation. Our libraries can be the community centers where these conversations, open dialogue, and civil debate should be encouraged and can occur. In S o c i a l j u s t i c e a n d t h e m e d i c a l l i b r a r i a n 3 0 1 DOI: dx.doi.org/10.5195/jmla.2019.712 jmla.mlanet.org 107 (3) July 2019 Journal of the Medical Library Association addition, we can provide the quality information and data to help participants in these conversations critically evaluate and sift out the fake news from the real news. It is our responsibility to provide access to accurate, trusted information as well as the tools and skills to critically evaluate that information in ways that promote diversity, equity, inclusion, and social justice. In addition, we need to collect, preserve, and make available information by, for, and about marginalized communities and fill in the gaps in the history of medical education. In 1962, British librarian Douglas John Foskett wrote The Creed of a Librarian: No Politics, No Religion, No Morals, in which he argued “the librarian ought virtually vanish as an individual person, except in so far as his personality sheds light on the working of the library” [39]. I disagree with Foskett. In my opinion, the notion of library neutrality is a myth. Our buying decisions, resources, budgets, and even locations are not neutral. We contribute to certain kinds of inequalities through our acquisitions decisions, our cataloging practices, our classification schemes, our controlled vocabularies, our use of commercial search engines, and even where we are located in our hospitals or academic campuses. We regularly practice self-censorship in book selection by primarily buying from corporate vendors. Neutrality is “a code word for the existing system. It has nothing to do with anything but agreeing to what is and will always be…Neutrality is just following the crowd” [40]. A neutral stance does not care about human rights violations. Neutrality does not account for social and economic inequalities. The notion that the medical library is a social institution that serves as a community center for its users is not neutral. Medical librarians cannot be neutral and be trusted advocates for their communities, especially the underserved. I believe that medical librarians can be forces for social good. This is crucial to our future and to the health of our local communities and a sustainable global community. What can medical librarians do? We need to move beyond awareness to action. We must address the whiteness of our profession and develop real strategies for doing so [36]. We must acknowledge that our libraries have never been and are not neutral. We must bring our libraries closer to the communities we serve. We need to confront the societal responsibilities of LIS and develop curricula that emphasize preparing future librarians for leadership roles in activism, community service and engagement, rights, and justice. We need to shift our focus to the people and communities we serve and de-emphasize collections. Medical librarians in partnership with medical educators can and should provide students with opportunities, resources, and spaces that encourage open dialogue on social issues, broaden their horizons, encourage empathy for patients, and use these experiences to make a difference. Medical librarians should embrace a humanistic approach to professional practice, one that embraces the whole person, not just the physician scientist, and supports curricular efforts that expand the humanities in medicine. We need to offer services, programs, and resources that reflect the diversity of the communities we serve and provide outreach to and advocacy for and with underserved communities in our local communities. We need to support open access publishing and advocate for policies that increase access to information for all [30]. Medical librarians, our professional associations, and LIS schools can take specific actions to promote social justice. We can offer open dialogues and discussions on social justice topics at our library conferences. We can develop hiring practices that recognize a variety of experiences, application formats, and interview styles to encourage diverse applicants to apply. We can commit to opening the pipeline into medical librarianship through innovative pathways for library assistants to attain the MLIS. We can make concerted efforts to hire staff from diverse backgrounds that reflect US census data. We must develop a welcoming and inclusive environment for all employees and library users in our workplaces. We must welcome all comers into our library conferences. We must develop an approach to professional practice that considers user needs and experiences first and offer library services, resources, and programs that reflect the needs of our users, especially those who may be marginalized. We can adopt a public history perspective to building special collections and archives, filling in the gaps. We can adopt and enforce practices and policies that show respect for ALL library users, even when these may be inconvenient for us. We must implement outreach and advocacy programs in equal partnership with underserved populations, respecting cultural norms, in order to increase access to health information throughout the world. In the LIS schools or 3 0 2 R u s s o M a r t i n DOI: dx.doi.org/10.5195/jmla.2019.712 Journal of the Medical Library Association 107 (3) July 2019 jmla.mlanet.org programs, we need to add courses into the curriculum that focus on diversity and social justice topics; and we need to increase the number of LIS faculty from diverse backgrounds. CONCLUSION —Injustice everywhere is a threat to justice everywhere. Martin Luther King [41] Librarian of Congress Archibald MacLeish said, “Librarians must become active not passive agents of the democratic process” [42]. Social justice and social responsibility are core values of the medical profession. Medical librarians have been an untapped resource for this important work. Diversity, inclusion, and social justice are the defining issues for the present and future of the medical library profession. Positive outcomes from this work will be cementing the relevance of the medical librarian as a member of the health care team. Medical librarians who practice their profession through a social justice lens have the potential to have a meaningful impact on transforming the health of the public, especially the marginalized. Medical librarians are no strangers to change and evolving roles. We have learned new technologies and adapted them into our library workflows. We have moved from a focus on print to electronic resources. We have added online searching, expert searching, systematic reviews, and in-person and online teaching to our portfolios. We work outside the library as informationists and are embedded into research or clinical teams. We have learned how to write data management plans and teach researchers and graduate students how to use electronic lab notebooks. Social justice medical librarianship is one more change in the evolution of our profession. We can do this. We must do this. The future of our profession depends on it. REFERENCES 1. Brandeis LD. Social Welfare History Project: True Americanism—address of Louis D. Brandeis (1915) [Internet]. Virginia Commonwealth University [cited 20 Mar 2019]. . 2. Gorman M. Our enduring values: librarianship in the 21st century. Chicago, IL: American Library Association; 2000. 3. Lemkau HL Jr. Constants, context, and change: the pursuit of purpose. J Med Libr Assoc. 2008 Jan;96(1):12–9. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.3163/1536-5050.96.1.12. 4. Zachert MJ. Books and other endangered species: an inquiry into the values of medical librarianship. Bull Med Libr Assoc. 1978 Oct;66(4):381–9. 5. Bishop D. On the uses of diversity. Bull Med Libr Assoc. 1976 Oct;64(4):349–55. 6. Brodman E. The pursuit of excellence. Bull Med Libr Assoc. 1971 Oct;59(4):549–54. 7. Anderson RK. Reinventing the medical librarian. Bull Med Libr Assoc. 1989 Oct;77(4):323–31. 8. Oppenheimer GJ. Domus or polis? the location of values. Bull Med Libr Assoc. 1988 Oct;76(4):306–16. 9. Klein A. Obama calls for ‘democracy with a small d.’ Washington, DC: World Net Daily [Internet]. 19 Sep 2012 [cited 20 Mar 2019]. . 10. O’Toole G. Of all the forms of inequality, injustice in health is the most shocking and inhuman [Internet]. Quote Investigator [22 Oct 2015; cited 25 Mar 2019]. . 11. Kumagai AK, Lypson ML. Beyond cultural competence: critical consciousness, social justice, and multicultural education. Acad Med. 2009 Jun;84(6):782–7. 12. Betancourt JR. Eliminating racial and ethnic disparities in health care: what is the role of academic medicine? Acad Med. 2006 Sep;81(9):788–92. 13. American College of Physicians. Racial and ethnic disparities in health care. Philadelphia, PA: The College; 2003. 14. Farmer P. Social scientists and the new tuberculosis. Soc Sci Med. 1997 Feb;44(3):347–58. 15. Liaison Committee on Medical Education. Functions and structure of a medical school: standards for accreditation of medical education programs leading to the MD degree [Internet]. Association of American Medical Colleges and the American Medical Association; 2017 [cited 1 Apr 2109]. . 16. Schiff T, Rieth K. Projects in medical education: “Social Justice in Medicine” a rationale for an elective program as part of the medical education curriculum at John A. Burns School of Medicine. Hawaii J Med Public Health. 2012 Apr;71(4 suppl 1):64–7. 17. Taylor R, Rieger A. Medicine as social science: Rudolf Virchow on the typhus epidemic in Upper Silesia. Int J Health Serv. 1985;15(4):547–59. 18. Ambrose AJ, Andaya JM, Yamada S, Maskarinec GG. Social justice in medical education: strengths and challenges of a student-driven social justice curriculum. Hawaii J Med Public Health. 2014 Aug;73(8):244–50. 19. Acosta D, Ackerman-Barger K. Breaking the silence: time to talk about race and racism. Acad Med. 2017 Mar;92(3):285– 8. S o c i a l j u s t i c e a n d t h e m e d i c a l l i b r a r i a n 3 0 3 DOI: dx.doi.org/10.5195/jmla.2019.712 jmla.mlanet.org 107 (3) July 2019 Journal of the Medical Library Association 20. Wear D, Zarconi J, Aultman JM, Chyatte MR, Kumagai AK. Remembering Freddie Gray: medical education for social justice. Acad Med. 2017 Mar;92(3):312–7. 21. Bakshi S, James A, Hennelly MO, Karani R, Palermo AG, Jakubowski A, Ciccariello C, Atkinson H. The Human Rights and Social Justice Scholars Program: a collaborative model for preclinical training in social medicine. Ann Glob Health. 2015 Mar–Apr;81(2):290–7. 22. Megivern LE. Political, not partisan: service-learning as social justice education. Vermont Connect. 2010 Jan;31(8):61–71. 23. Halman M, Baker L, Ng S. Using critical consciousness to inform health professions education: a literature review. Perspect Med Educ. 2017 Feb;6(1):12–20. 24. Kumagai AK. From competencies to human interests: ways of knowing and understanding in medical education. Acad Med. 2014 Jul;89(7):978–83. 25. Freire P. Pedagogy of the oppressed. 30th anniversary ed. New York, NY: Continuum; 2000. 26. DasGupta S, Fornari A, Geer K, Hahn L, Kumar V, Lee HJ, Rubin S, Gold M. Medical education for social justice: Paulo Freire revisited. J Med Humanit. 2006 Winter;27(4):245–51. 27. McCarthy TA. The critical theory of Jürgen Habermas. 1st MIT Press paperback ed. Cambridge: MIT Press; 1981. 28. Terry PR. Habermas and education: knowledge, communication, discourse. Curric Studies. 1997 Dec 20;5(3):269–79. 29. Tulshyan R. Why diversity matters [Internet]. Burlington, NC: Diversity Woman [cited 20 Mar 2019]. . 30. Bourg C. Diversity, inclusion, social justice and libraries: proposing a framework. Feral Libr [Internet]. [18 Apr 2016; cited 20 Mar 2019]. . 31. Schonfeld RC, Sweeney L. Inclusion, diversity, and equity: members of the Association of Research Libraries: employee demographics and director perspectives [Internet]. Ithaka S+R; 2017 [cited 1 Apr 2019]. . 32. American Library Association. Diversity counts [Internet]. Chicago, IL: The Association [cited 20 Mar 2019]. . 33. Meeks LM, Jain NR. Accessibility, inclusion, and action in medical education: lived experiences of learners and physicians with disabilities. Washington, DC: Association of American Medical Colleges; 2018. 34. Vinopal J. The quest for diversity in library staffing: from awareness to action. Libr Lead Pipe [Internet]. 13 Jan 2016 [cited 20 Mar 2019]. . 35. Lance KC. Racial and ethnic diversity of U.S. library workers. Am Libr. 2005 May:41–3. (Available from: . [cited 1 Apr 2019].) 36. Hathcock A. White librarianship in blackface: diversity initiatives in LIS. Libr Lead Pipe [Internet]. 7 Oct 2015 [cited 20 Mar 2019]. . 37. Ginn DS. The AIDS information crisis: confluence of the roles of information creator, seeker, and provider. Bull Med Libr Assoc. 1987 Oct; 75(4): 333–41. 38. Emery D. Did Martin Luther King say ‘our lives begin to end the day we become silent’? [Internet]. Snopes Media Group [16 Jan 2017; cited Mar 25 2019]. . 39. Foskett DJ. The creed of a librarian—no politics, no religion, no morals. London, UK: Library Association; 1962. 40. Horton M, Freire P, Bell B, Gaventa J, Peters JM, eds. We make the road by walking: conversations on education and social change. Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press; 1990. 41. King ML Jr. Letter from Birmingham jail. Liberation. 1963;8(4):10–6. 42. MacLeish A. The librarian and the democratic process. ALA Bulletin. 1940 Jun:388. AUTHOR’S AFFILIATION Elaine Russo Martin, FMLA, elaine_martin@hms.harvard.edu, Director of Library Services, Countway Library, Harvard Medical School, Boston, MA Received March 2019; accepted March 2019 Articles in this journal are licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License. This journal is published by the University Library System of the University of Pittsburgh as part of its D-Scribe Digital Publishing Program and is cosponsored by the University of Pittsburgh Press. ISSN 1558-9439 (Online) Elaine Russo Martin, FMLA See end of article for author’s affiliation. This lecture discusses social justice and the role that medical librarians can play in a democratic society. Social justice needs to be central to the mission of medical librarianship and a core value of the profession. Medical librarians must develop a new professional orientation: one that focuses on cultural awareness or cultural consciousness that goes beyond ourselves and our collections to that which focuses on the users of our libraries. We must develop a commitment to addressing the issues of societal, relevant health information. Using examples from medical education, this lecture makes the case for social justice librarianship. This lecture also presents a pathway for social justice medical librarianship, identifies fundamental roles and activities in these areas, and offers strategies for individual librarians, the Medical Library Association, and library schools for developing social justice education and outcomes. The lecture advocates for an understanding of and connection to social justice responsibilities for the medical library profession and ends with a call to go beyond understanding to action. The lecture emphasizes the lack of diversity in our profession and the importance of diversity and inclusion for achieving social justice. The lecture presents specific examples from some medical libraries to extend the social justice mindset and to direct outreach, collections, archives, and special collection services to expose previously hidden voices. If medical librarians are to remain relevant in the future, we must act to address the lack of diversity in our profession and use our information resources, spaces, and expertise to solve the relevant societal issues of today. INTRODUCTION DEFINING SOCIAL JUSTICE SOCIAL JUSTICE AND MEDICAL SCHOOL CURRICULUM THE CASE FOR SOCIAL JUSTICE AND THE MEDICAL LIBRARIAN THE SOCIAL JUSTICE EDUCATION DEBATE DIVERSITY IN LIBRARIANSHIP SOCIAL JUSTICE IN MEDICAL LIBRARIANSHIP CALL TO ACTION CONCLUSION References Author’s Affiliation Elaine Russo Martin, FMLA, elaine_martin@hms.harvard.edu, Director of Library Services, Countway Library, Harvard Medical School, Boston, MA Received March 2019; accepted March 2019 work_6ye3a4zyrvaa3ggevr46bquduu ---- 1719 При цитировании этой статьи ссылка на doi обязательна © N O TA B E N E (О О О « Н Б -М ед иа ») w w w .n bp ub lis h. co m DOI: 10.7256/1999-2793.2014.12.13053 НОВАЯ НАУЧНАЯ ПАРАДИГМА Феномен ноосФеры: эволюционный подход и глобальное измерение а.д. Урсул DOI: 10.7256/1999-2793.2014.12.13053 Введение В первой� половйне прошлого века россйй� скйй� уче- ный� академйк В.И. Вернадскйй� й два французскйх ученых – П. Тей� яр де Шарден й Э. Леруа выдвйну- лй йдею становленйя сферы разума – ноосферы в качестве главного направленйя дальней� шего раз- вйтйя человечества, которое должно рацйоналй- зйровать цйвйлйзацйонный� процесс, обеспечйть выжйванйе цйвйлйзацйй. В.И. Вернадскйй� предсказал, что научная мысль обрете� т «планетный� » (глобальный� ) харак- тер. И конкретные очертанйя этого предсказанйя мы вйдйм как в ныне пройсходящйх глобальных процессах в мйре й йх осмысленйй, так й в пред- вйденйй й йсследованйй будущйх соцйальных й соцйопрйродных эволюцйонных процессов. В.И. Вернадскйй� сей� час вйдйтся в качестве велй- кого мыслйтеля глобальной� эпохй, которая в пер- спектйве становйтся также эпохой� ноосферы1. 1 См.: Ильин И.В., Урсул А.Д. В.И. Вернадский – основопо- ложник глобальных исследований // Вестник Московского университета. Серия XXVII. Глобалистика и геополити- Аннотация. В статье выстраивается единая эволюционно-информационная концепция становления ноосферы не только как планетарного феномена, но и как необходимого этапа вселенского процесса самоорганизации ма- терии. Сфера разума представляется автором как ещё не существующее, а гипотетическое будущее состоя- ние общества и его взаимодействия с природой, в котором приоритетное место будет занимать глобальный общечеловеческий интеллект, направляющий социоприродную эволюцию в безопасно-поступательном на- правлении. Раскрывается процесс перехода человечества к устойчивому развитию, информационная сущность феномена ноосферы и становления её главного ядра – коллективного ноосферного интеллекта. Отмечается, что учение о ноосфере в трудах В.И. Вернадского развивалось на концептуальной основе, в которой глобализм и идеи становления ноосферы оказались соединенными в целостную форму мировоззрения. Ноосферогенез рас- сматривается в работе как основное средство и форма выживания человечества и как главная цель всего со- временного и будущего цивилизационного развития, включая переход к глобальной устойчивости, созидание информационной цивилизации, глобализацию и другие позитивные процессы глобального развития. Автор так- же анализирует новые мегатенденции ноосферогенеза в области науки, образования, культуры, управления с учетом достижений современных научных исследований и прогнозирования перспектив дальнейшей эволюции мировой цивилизации. В работе используются эволюционный (в особенности универсально-эволюционный) под- ход и методы глобальных исследований, а также информационный подход и критерий развития. Показано так- же, что в рамках исследования будущего ноосферно-футурологический подход может кардинальным образом изменить и традиционные подходы и способы исследования, ориентируя научный поиск в области прошлого и настоящего в сторону осознания и прогнозирования будущего. Высказывается мнение, что человечество уже начинает превращаться в единую, целостную цивилизацию ноосферы, сопровождаемую формированием прин- ципиально нового безопасного социоприродного коэволюционного способа взаимодействия. Также речь идёт о том, что социальная и социоприродная эволюция создает возможности становления сферы разума не только в биосфере. Ноосферогенез как будущий глобальный процесс выступает как необходимый этап глобальной эво- люции в мироздании, которая будет реализоваться в социоприродной и социокультурной формах вначале на Земле, а затем и в пространствах Вселенной. Ключевые слова: глобальное, глобальная эволюция, информация, информационный критерий, культура, ноосфера, ноосферогенез, ноосферный интеллект, цефализация, эволюционный подход. Философия и культура 12(84) • 2014 1720 При цитировании этой статьи ссылка на doi обязательна © N O TA B E N E (О О О « Н Б -М ед иа ») w w w .n bp ub lis h. co m DOI: 10.7256/1999-2793.2014.12.13053 Концепцйй сферы разума, йлй ноосферы, ко- торые былй предложены йх основоположнйкамй, существенно разлйчалйсь между собой� . Однако все онй ймелй некоторое общее содержанйе й йс- следовательскую орйентацйю – веру в сйлу разума (не только человеческого) й представленйе йнтел- лекта в его разлйчных формах в качестве главного двйжущего механйзма последующей� уже «целесо- образно-разумной� » эволюцйй. Хотя термйн «но- осфера» не употреблялся К.Э. Цйолковскйм, тем не менее, он также говорйл о ролй разума во Все- ленной� , полагая, что мысль оказывается не только геологйческйм фактором (о чем пйсал В.И. Вернад- скйй� ), но й станет решающйм фактором в эволю- цйй космоса. Идея об усйленйй ролй разума в развйтйй об- щества не является достоянйем лйшь конца трйд- цатых годов XX века, когда французскйй� ученый� й фйлософ Э. Леруа, а затем его соотечественнйк П. Тей� яр де Шарден й В.И. Вернадскйй� сталй йс- пользовать понятйе «ноосфера». Прйчем В.И. Вер- надскйй� прйзнавал прйорйтет упомянутых свойх коллег во введенйй тепмйна «ноосфера». Так, во фрагменте «Несколько слов о ноосфере» он отме- чает: «Прйняв установленную мною бйогехймйче- скую основу бйосферы за йсходное, французскйй� математйк й фйлософ бергсонйанец Е. Ле-Руа в свойх лекцйях в Коллеж де Франс в Парйже ввел в 1927 г. понятйе «ноосферы» как современной� стадйй, геологйческй пережйваемой� бйосферой� . Он подчеркйвал прй этом, что он прйшел к тако- му представленйю вместе со свойм другом, круп- ней� шйм геологом й палеонтологом Тельяром де- Шарденом, работающйм теперь в Кйтае»2. Не стойт жестко прйвязывать ноосферные йдей, концепцйй й двйженйя к термйну «ноосфера», ймея также в вйду, что этй йдей й теченйя с самого начала своего генезйса является международнымй, теперь даже глобальнымй. Роль й место разумного начала в соцйальной� деятельностй определяет ста- новленйе ноосферной� йдей, начйная с антйчностй, а тем более, когда сталй прйменяться такйе термйны как «царство разума» (просветйтелй), «мйр разума» (мондйалйсты), йнформацйонное общество, обще- ка. 2013. № 1; Урсул А.Д. Мыслитель глобальной эпохи (К 150-летию со дня рождения В.И. Вернадского) // NB: Фило- софские исследования. 2013. № 9. С. 1-63. (URL: http://e- notabene.ru/fr/article_805.html). 2 Вернадский В.И. Научная мысль как планетное явление. М., 1991. С. 241. ство знанйя йлй же более прйнятый� в Россйй тер- мйн «ноосфера». Поэтому «ноосферное двйженйе» оказывается более шйрокйм, чем те йсследованйя, которые йспользуют ставшйй� уже традйцйонным термйн «ноосфера». В настоящей� работе далее развйваются осно- вополагающйе йдей В.И. Вернадского о ноосфере, но вместе с тем йде� т определенное расшйренйе концептуального вйденйя феномена ноосферы до глобальных й эволюцйонно-космйческйх масшта- бов. Речь будет йдтй не только о том, что бйосфера создает возможностй становленйя сферы разума, но й о том, что появленйе ноосферы обусловлено глобальной� эволюцйей� во Вселенной� . Обсуждают- ся также новые мегатенденцйй становленйя сфе- ры разума как ноосферогенеза, йлй ноосферного развйтйя с учетом достйженйй� современной� наукй й прогнозйрованйя перспектйв дальней� шего раз- вйтйя глобальных й космйческйх процессов. Работа носйт концептуальный� характер, по- скольку раскрывается й аргументйруется ранее высказанная автором йдея о том, что становленйе ноосферы выступает в качестве необходймого зве- на глобально-унйверсальной� эволюцйй как все- ленского процесса самоорганйзацйй в мйрозданйй. Прй этом выявляется важная роль йнформацйон- ных процессов, факторов й крйтерйев развйтйя, прйчем не только на соцйальном этапе эволюцйй, но й в более шйроком – глобально-эволюцйонном ракурсе. Становленйе ноосферы представляется не только как нейзбежный� этап на путй планетар- ного развйтйя, но й как продолженйя глобальной� эволюцйй, ее� основной� траекторйй – так называ- емой� супермагйстралй, характерйзующей� ся ро- стом сложностй й накопленйем йнформацйонного содержанйя все� более высокйх структур й сйстем в ходе йх самоорганйзацйй. Ноосферный� этап гло- бальной� эволюцйй наступает, когда в цйвйлйзацйй появляется не только огромное йнформацйонное содержанйе, но й появляется новое качество йн- формацйонно-йнтеллектуальных процессов, осо- бенно появленйя свой� ства опереженйя глобально- коллектйвным йнтеллектом своего бытйя. Основные йдей этой� работы сложйлйсь под влйянйем осмысленйя существенного «взрыва» йсследованйй� творчества В.И. Вернадского в связй с празднованйем в прошлом году 150-летйя со дня его рожденйя, который� шйроко отмечался в науч- ных й другйх юбйлей� ных меропрйятйях в нашей� стране. В этйх йсследованйях й меропрйятйях прй- 1721 При цитировании этой статьи ссылка на doi обязательна © N O TA B E N E (О О О « Н Б -М ед иа ») w w w .n bp ub lis h. co m DOI: 10.7256/1999-2793.2014.12.13053 новая научная парадигма лйчйе точкй зренйя В.И. Вернадского от его уже упомянутых коллег. Такое пространственное й вместе с тем – со- цйопрйродное расшйренйе расшйренйе сферы разума за пределы соцйума ймеет теоретйко-ме- тодологйческйе основанйя: ведь огранйченйе сфе- ры разума только обществом вовсе не означает, это последнее веде� т себя разумно по отношенйю к прйроде. И это демонстрйрует современная гло- бально-экологйческая сйтуацйя, которая стре- мйтельно ухудшается в современной� моделй не- устой� чйвого развйтйя6. Сей� час же цйвйлйзацйя, формально состоящая йз более, чем двух сотен суверенных государств, й 7 млрд. автономных йн- дйвйдов, судорожно «цепляясь» за старую модель развйтйя, неуклонно двйжется к своему трагйче- скому фйналу – глобальной� соцйально-экологйче- ской� катастрофе – й в этом трагйческое протйво- речйе неустой� чйвого развйтйя. Последнее десятйлетйе прошлого века внесло важные корректйвы в понйманйе процесса ста- новленйя ноосферы. Ноосфера – не просто сфера распространенйя человека разумного разумного (даже найменованйе которого Homo sapiens сей� час стало подвергаться серьезным сомненйям й дйс- куссйям7). Ноосфера, как полагал В.И. Вернадскйй� , представляется как «новое геологйческое явленйе на нашей� планете. В ней� впервые человек стано- вйтся крупней� шей� геологйческой� сйлой� . Он может й должен перестрайвать свойм трудом й мыслью область своей� жйзнью, перестрайвать коренным образом по сравненйю с тем, что было раньше. Пе- ред нйм открываются все� более й более шйрокйе творческйе возможностй»8. Здесь ученый� рассма- трйвает ноосферогенез как продолженйе геологй- ческой� эволюцйй, в которой� крупней� шей� геологй- ческой� сйлой� выступает уже не только бйота, но й человечество. Однако вряд лй ймеет смысл называть ноос- ферой� прошлую йлй современную соцйосферу, где самым совершенным тйпом разума обладает лйшь отдельный� нормальный� йндйвйд. Это будет лйшь 6 См.: GEO-5. Глобальная экологическая перспектива. Ре- зюме для политиков. Найроби: ЮНЕП, 2012. 7 См.: Прозоров Л.Л. Было ли учение Вернадского о ноос- фере? // Пространство и время. 2012. № 4. Универсальная и глобальная история (эволюция Вселенной, Земли, жизни, общества). Волгоград, 2012. С. 677. 8 Вернадский В.И. Научная мысль как планетное явление. М., 1991. С. 241. нял участйе й автор, обнаружйвшйй� новые черты й особенностй творческого наследйя ученого как в областй его ученйя о ноосфере, так й установйв- шйй� прйорйтетность й глобальную направлен- ность многйх его научных йсследованйй� 3. Пространственно-временные контуры становления сферы разума Важной� особенностью ноосферной� йдей В.И. Вер- надского является выясненйе ролй разума не толь- ко в жйзнй общества, но через него в эволюцйй бйосферы (особенно геологйческой� й бйосферной� эволюцйй). В прйнцйпе йдея ноосферогенеза как становленйя сферы разума отлйчается от йдей ноогенеза (которая была предложена П. Тей� яром де Шарденом4) тем, что в первом случае ноогенез рассматрйвается совместно с трансформацйямй окружающей� его среды. Это напомйнает йдею бйо- сферы (теорйя которой� была существенно развй- та Вернадскйм5), когда бйота включается в сферу взаймодей� ствующего с ней� косного вещества. И такая йдея оказывается в эволюцйонном плане бо- лее адекватной� , поскольку развйтйе соцйума, тем более прогрессйвное, в сйлу сйнергетйческйх со- ображенйй� следует рассматрйвать как соразвйтйе, желательно, как коэволюцйю сйстемы совместно с прйродной� средой� , за счет которой� оно пройсходйт. Тем самым речь должна йдтй йменно о ноос- ферогенезе, а не о ноогенезе, как об этом пйшет в своей� кнйге «Феномен человека» П. Тей� яр де Шарден, уделяя внйманйе в основном развйтйю сознанйя, процессу йнтеллектуалйзацйй матерйй в ходе эволюцйй. Ноосферогенез – более шйрокое й адекватное понятйе, чем ноогенез, поскольку он касается не только духовно-йнтеллектуальной� составляющей� ноосферы, но й матерйальной� , не только культурно-йнформацйонной� , но й веще- ственно-энергетйческой� – й это существенное от- 3 См.: Ильин И.В., Урсул А.Д. В.И. Вернадский – основопо- ложник глобальных исследований // Вестник Московского университета. Серия XXVII: Глобалистика и геополитика. 2013. № 1; Они же. Глобальные исследования и эволюци- онный подход. М.: МГУ, 2013; Ильин И.В., Урсул А.Д., Ур- сул Т.А. Глобалистика и глобальные исследования. Гло- бальная революция в науке. Saarbrucken, Germany. Dictus Publishing. 2014; Урсул А.Д. Феномен ноосферы: Глобальная эволюция и ноосферогенез. М., 2014. 4 См.: Тейяр де Шарден П. Феномен человека. M., 1987. 5 См.: Вернадский В.И. Биосфера и ноосфера. М., 2004. Философия и культура 12(84) • 2014 1722 При цитировании этой статьи ссылка на doi обязательна © N O TA B E N E (О О О « Н Б -М ед иа ») w w w .n bp ub lis h. co m DOI: 10.7256/1999-2793.2014.12.13053 значйтельная часть бйосферы, в то время когда остальная часть будет сохраняться, что требует пе- реход к устой� чйвому развйтйю (УР). Планетарный� характер становленйя сферы разума (прйнцйп ноо- глобалйзма) определяется не только глобалйзацй- ей� й бйосферно-экологйческймй соображенйямй, а фактйческй всемй основнымй составляющймй сй- стемы глобальной� деятельностй как глобального развйтйя. Однако смысл понятйя «глобальный� » может существенно меняться в завйсймостй от тйпа гло- бальных йсследованйй� . Счйтать же, что во всей� науке следует употреблять термйн «глобальный� » в одном й том же смысле было бы просто нере- алйстйчным. Омонймйя й полйсемйя термйнов является обычным феноменом как обыденного, так й научного языка й она отнюдь не уменьшает- ся с развйтйем наукй, она характерна й для всего спектра современных глобальных йсследованйй� . Казалось бы, глобальнымй процессамй можно на- зывать процессы, пройсходящйе в пределах нашей� планеты, обнаружйвающйе определенную «гло- бальную целостность», лйбо стремящйеся к ней� . В этом смысле глобальные процессы – это не просто процессы, пройсходящйе на Земле, а общеплане- тарные процессы, т.е. охватывающйе всю планету в целом. Однако важно обратйть внйманйе на суще- ствующую «дйхотомйю», лйнгвйстйческую двус- мысленность термйна «глобальный� ». Термйн «глобальный� » этймологйческй пройсходйт не йз одного, а йз двух языков – латйнского («globus» – шар) й французского (global – всеобщйй� , взятый� в целом). И в современной� науке термйн «гло- бальный� » употребляется в основном в этйх двух «пространственных» смыслах: 1) глобальный� как планетарный� , относящйй� ся к земному шару й 2) глобальный� как всеохватывающйй� , унйверсаль- ный� , всеобщйй� , взятый� в целом, й в этом смыс- ле уже распространяется на все мйрозданйе, йлй на всю Вселенную. Соответственно, глобальные процессы могут мыслйться в этйх двух основных значенйях: 1) глобальные процессы как в целом развертывающйеся на земном шаре, т.е. общепла- нетарные процессы, 2) глобальные процессы как процессы, охватывающйе все мйрозданйе, по край� - ней� мере, ту его часть, которая относйтся к вйдй- мой� , йлй вещественной� Вселенной� . Однако есть й еще� одйн смысл термйна «гло- бальный� », который� означает, что данный� про- цесс (объект) обладает какой� -то всеобщей� со- простое перейменованйе соцйосферы в ноосферу, которое нйкак не йзменяет степень разумностй всего человечества, которое по-прежнему будет стремйться к своей� экологйческой� , ядерной� йлй йной� форме стйхйй� но-коллектйвного, как теперь уже ясно, глобального самоубйй� ства. Важно сфор- мйровать прйнцйпйально новый� – не только йндй- вйдуальный� , но й качественно более высокйй� , уже общечеловеческйй� – глобально-ноосферный� йн- теллект, способный� вывестй цйвйлйзацйю йз крй- зйса, предотвратйть возможные планетарные й космйческйе катастрофы. Грозящйе человечеству опасностй й угрозы, особенно глобально-космйче- ского характера, заставляют развйваться челове- ческому йнтеллекту, прйнймать коллектйвные й глобальные формы существованйя й функцйонй- рованйя. Ноосфера (от греч. νό� ός – «разум» й σφαῖρα – «шар») вйдйтся как гйпотетйческое будущее состо- янйе (й вместе с тем дальней� шйй� глобальный� про- цесс) общества й его взаймодей� ствйя с прйродой� , в котором прйорйтетное место будет занймать кол- лектйвный� общечеловеческйй� разум, йменуемый� ноосферным йнтеллектом, направляющйй� эволю- цйю цйвйлйзацйй в прогрессйвно-поступательном й безопасном направленйй (о че� м подробнее пой� - дет речь дальше). Ныне ймеющйй� ся, но трудно определймый� со- вокупный� йнтеллект всего человечества гораздо менее эффектйвен йндйвйдуального йнтеллекта, еслй йметь в вйду здорового нормального чело- века, а не больного лйбо девйантного йндйвйда, стремящегося к суйцйду. Помймо прочего, это свя- зано с отсутствйем необходймых взаймосвязей� между частямй мйрового соцйума (которые йме- ются на уровне йндйвйда), й которые появляются в процессе глобалйзацйй. Вот почему «коллектй- вйзацйя» разума вплоть до обретенйя йм нового качества й целостностй в процессе будущего ноос- ферогенеза преследует цель распространйть более рацйональное (эффектйвное) поведенйе на всю человеческую цйвйлйзацйю й ее взаймодей� ствйе с прйродой� : «лучшее понйманйе й переход от по- нйманйя к дей� ствйю – йменно такую цйвйлйзацйю мы охарактерйзовалй бы как более разумную»9. Характерной� чертой� будущей� ноосферы ока- жется ее глобальный� характер, даже в том случае, еслй в сферу разума будет превращаться лйшь не- 9 Вайцзеккер Э., Ловинс Э., Ловинс Л. Фактор четыре. За- трат – половина, отдача – двойная. М., 2000. С. 353. 1723 При цитировании этой статьи ссылка на doi обязательна © N O TA B E N E (О О О « Н Б -М ед иа ») w w w .n bp ub lis h. co m DOI: 10.7256/1999-2793.2014.12.13053 новая научная парадигма бйосфера й существующая на ней� соцйосфера бу- дут превращаться в сферу разума, но й внеземное пространство й небесные тела. Именно так по мере становленйя ноосферы й освоенйя космоса будет формйроваться космоноосфера, поэтому й в сйлу этого, пусть й весьма отдаленного этапа ноосферо- генеза, не только бйосфера будет превращаться в ноосферу. Однако, опять-такй важно подчеркнуть, что ноосферное будущее мыслйтся чаще всего в его глобально-планетарной� форме: соцйальная ступень эволюцйй, выходя в космос, будет в пер- вую очередь йскать й освайвать планеты, подоб- ные нашей� Земле, где й предполагается ее� про- странственно-темпоральное продолженйе. Пространственное расшйренйе соцйаль- ной� ступенй вызвано, прежде всего, тем, что ее сущность ймеет прйнцйпйально культурно-йн- формацйонный� характер, отлйчающйй� ся от йн- формацйонно-содержательных характерйстйк бйологйческой� ступенй налйчйем особой� надын- дйвйдуальной� й внелйчностной� сйстемы средств генерацйй, накопленйя, храненйя й преобразова- нйя йнформацйй, необходймой� для органйзацйй соцйальной� деятельностй, т.е. культуры (на чем далее я еще� остановлюсь). Именно этот прейму- щественно внеорганйзменный� , экзогенно-йнфор- мацйонный� характер формйрованйя человеческой� культуры й вызывает расшйренйе сферы челове- ческой� деятельностй вначале на планете, а затем й в космосе. Расшйренйе планетарных масштабов деятель- ностй человека в глобальном йзмеренйй должно быть связано с ее значймостью для человечества в целом, т.е. чем больше масштабы человеческой� деятельностй, тем больше эта деятельность долж- на способствовать выжйванйю й устой� чйвому раз- вйтйю цйвйлйзацйй в целом. Последующйе этапы ноосферогенеза предполагают решенйе новых как глобальных проблем, так й космйческйх по мере продвйженйя эволюцйонного процесса во внезем- ные пространства. Понйманйе того, что представляет собой� ноос- фера, завйсйт прежде всего от обнаруженйя начала ее появленйя (как, впрочем, й наоборот): сйтуацйя здесь аналогйчна с понйманйем глобалйзацйй, где начало этого глобального процесса прямо завйсйт от определенйя его понятйя. Ноосферу в современ- ной� лйтературе представляют в двух основных темпоральных варйантах: как уже существующую сферу распространенйя й обйтанйя человека раз- умного й как гйпотетйческое будущее состоянйе держательной� характерйстйкой� , свой� ством йлй параметром, которому подчйняются абсолютно все существующйе процессы й объекты. Напрймер, все объекты вещественного фрагмента Вселенной� обладают тяготенйем йлй пространством с тремя йзмеренйямй. Илй все людй, населяющйе планету, даже еслй онй еще� не объедйнены в некую гло- бально-целостную сйстему, подчйняются в своем развйтйй какйм-то общйм соцйальным законо- мерностям. Можно сказать, что общйе закономер- ностй, которые свой� ственны всем без йсключенйя йндйвйдам й йх сообществам (соцйумам) также являются йх глобальнымй характерйстйкамй в том смысле, что онй прйсущй всему соцйальному двйженйю й развйтйю. Сравнйвая этй значенйя термйна «глобаль- ный� » (пространственные й всеобще-содержатель- ный� ), можно догадаться, что этот качественно-со- держательный� смысл термйна оказывается более глубокйм й всеохватывающйм. Ведь еслй какйе- лйбо соцйальные процессы еще не обрелй своей� глобальной� целостностй, напрймер, в простран- ственном аспекте, то онй йзначально, по самой� сво- ей� прйроде обладают темй йлй йнымй всеобще-це- лостнымй содержательнымй свой� ствамй, которые в этом случае оказываются атрйбутйвнымй обще- человеческймй характерйстйкамй й параметрамй. Ясно, что атрйбутйвно-содержательный� , ка- чественный� крйтерйй� глобальностй оказывает- ся более «сйльным» й существенным, чем «про- странственно-колйчественные», одйн йз которых на нашей� планете совпадает с географйческйм крйтерйем. Онтологйческй «качественно-атрйбу- тйвная глобальность» относйтся к содержательно- сущностной� стороне объекта йлй процесса, к его прйроде й качественной� определенностй, прйсуща йм йзначально й всегда (по край� ней� мере, с тех пор как онй появйлйсь). В этом смысле глобальность как атрйбут какого-лйбо матерйального процесса йлй предмета – это его внутренняя, «экзйстенцй- альная» глобальность, тогда как «колйчественый� » крйтерйй� в дальней� шем проявляется как про- странственное расшйренйе этого содержательно- качественного крйтерйя. Глобальность того йлй йного процесса в пространственном смысле суще- ствует не всегда, й об этом красноречйво свйде- тельствуют йсследованйя процесса глобалйзацйй, как й не существующйй� пока феномен ноосферы. Можно, следуя К.Э. Цйолковскому, вйдеть ноосферогенез й в космйческой� перспектйве, в каком-то смысле говорйть о том, что не только Философия и культура 12(84) • 2014 1724 При цитировании этой статьи ссылка на doi обязательна © N O TA B E N E (О О О « Н Б -М ед иа ») w w w .n bp ub lis h. co m DOI: 10.7256/1999-2793.2014.12.13053 а прйверженцамй старой� моделй развйтйя фактйче- скй йгнорйруется лйбо даже отрйцается. Роль формйрованйя целей� дальней� шего УР человечества была осознана на недавнем саммйте Рйо+20, подтвердйвшего прйверженность курсу на устой� чйвое развйтйе й на обеспеченйе постро- енйя экономйческй, соцйально й экологйческй устой� чйвого будущего для нашей� планеты й для нынешнйх й будущйх поколенйй� . В йюне 2012 г. Конференцйя ООН по УР (Рйо+20) опять в Рйо-де- Жаней� ро прйняла решенйе о формулйрованйй но- вых целей� развйтйя цйвйлйзацйй (вместо завер- шающйхся Целей� развйтйя тысячелетйя в 2015 г.) для прйданйя деятельностй в областй устой� чйво- го развйтйя целенаправленного й последователь- ного характера. Такой� комплекс целей� в областй УР, отвечающего нормам международного права й опйрающегося на уже прйнятые обязательства й все предшествующйе документы ООН, способство- вал бы более полному осуществленйю решенйй� всех основных встреч на высшем уровне по эконо- мйческой� , соцйальной� й экологйческой� проблема- тйке УР, включая положенйя йтогового документа саммйта Рйо+2012. Исследованйе будущего УР й другйх глобаль- ных процессов в мйре в значйтельной� степенй об- условйлй й процесс футурйзацйй наукй, образова- нйя, управленйя й человеческой� деятельностй в целом. Дело в том, что расшйренйе сферы деятель- ностй на глобальные масштабы влече� т за собой� футурйзацйю, т.е. усйленйе внйманйя к будущему. Одной� йз самых кардйнальных трансформацйй� мй- рового развйтйя будет его футурйзацйя как про- цесс поворота наукй, йнформацйонных процессов й значйтельной� частй человеческой� деятельностй к будущему, й прежде всего речь йдет о включенйй фактора будущего в процесс духовно-йнтеллекту- ального освоенйя мйра й тем самым – процесс но- осферогенеза. Акцент научных (особенно глобальных) йссле- дованйй� на будущем не случаен: глобальная ката- строфа (лйбо череда регйональных катаклйзмов), которая может наступйть уже в XXI в., не даст шан- сов человечеству лйквйдйровать ее последствйя, как это делается сей� час, когда наступают локаль- ные катастрофы й чрезвычай� ные сйтуацйй, а за- тем устраняются йх последствйя. Глобальную (й 12 См.: Итоговый документ Конференции ООН по устойчи- вому развитию «Будущее, которого мы хотим» (URL: http:// www.un.org/ru/sustainablefuture). (й вместе с тем дальней� шйй� развертывающйй� - ся глобальный� процесс) всего человечества й его взаймодей� ствйя с прйродой� . Именно в этйх двух варйантах мыслйлй ноосферу не только Э. Леруа й Тей� яр де Шарден, но й В.И. Вернадскйй� (зачастую отдавая предпочтенйе ее� существованйю в насто- ящее время). Уче� ный� полагал, что становленйе ноосферы – это естественно-йсторйческйй� , нейз- бежный� эволюцйонный� геологйческйй� процесс, появляющйй� ся стйхйй� но как все предшествующйе разлйчные этапы геологйческой� эволюцйй й фор- мацйй в йсторйй человечества. Однако предложенное В.И. Вернадскйм расшй- ренйе чйсто «соцйального» представленйя сферы разума до «соцйопрйродного» понйманйя этого феномена вносйт важные корректйвы в вйденйе процесса ноосферогенеза. Ноосфера оказывается не просто сферой� распространенйя человека. Ученый� рассматрйвает ноосферогенез не только как чйсто соцйальные йлй только духовно-йнтеллектуальные трансформацйй, но й как продолженйе бйосферно- геологйческой� эволюцйй, в которой� крупней� шей� геологйческой� сйлой� выступает человечество. Человеческая йсторйя благодаря созйданйю ноосферы не станет огранйчйваться только про- шлым, настоящйм й весьма огранйченным буду- щйм. Найболее гуманной� перспектйвой� выглядйт продолженйе человеческого бытйя на неогранй- ченно длйтельные времена в будущее, как об этом мечтал К.Э. Цйолковскйй� 10. В.И. Вернадскйй� также весьма оптймйстйчно относйлся к будущему чело- вечества в ноосферной� форме его развйтйя, пола- гая, что: «будущее человека всегда большей� частью создае� тся йм самйм»11. И оба ученых предложйлй свой способы й формы продленйя существованйя человечества в будущее. А прйнятая в конце прошлого века стратегйя устой� чйвого развйтйя (УР), которая направлена на решенйе соцйопрйродных глобальных проблем пе- рехода к ноосфере, – это фактйческй переход от стй- хйй� но-антропофобной� нынешней� формы развйтйя к более гуманной� й управляемой� форме, которая может йсключйть йз будущей� йсторйй цйвйлйза- цйй ее трагйческйй� фйнал. Как вйдйм, рассмотре- нйе проблем перехода к УР существенно повышает йнтерес к проблеме будущего, которому в современ- ной� академйческой� науке уделяется мало внйманйя, 10 См.: Циолковский К.Э. Космическая философия. М., 2001. 11 Вернадский В.И. Открытия и судьбы. М., 1993. С. 484. 1725 При цитировании этой статьи ссылка на doi обязательна © N O TA B E N E (О О О « Н Б -М ед иа ») w w w .n bp ub lis h. co m DOI: 10.7256/1999-2793.2014.12.13053 новая научная парадигма Еслй глобальные процессы й прежде всего гло- балйзацйя воспрйнймаются как пространственное расшйренйе по земному шару й сйстемное объ- едйненйе, обретенйе целостностй человечества в процессе образованйя связей� между фрагментамй мйрового соцйума, то переход к УР, скорее всего, вйдйтся как глобальный� процесс продолженйя су- ществованйя цйвйлйзацйй во временй. Тем самым речь йдет об оптймйзацйй й реалйзацйй прйнцйпа темпоральной� целостностй существованйя й даль- ней� шего развйтйя цйвйлйзацйй. Глобальное развйтйе через УР ноосферной� орйентацйй предстает как едйный� пространствен- но-временной� процесс дальней� шего безопасного существованйя й сохраненйя эволюцйонно-гене- тйческой� целостностй человеческого рода. Прй- орйтетным выступает обеспеченйе безопасностй развертыванйя глобальных цйвйлйзацйонных процессов в прогрессйвно-поступательном на- правленйй, что гарантйрует возможность й спо- собность человечества к самосохраненйю й даль- ней� шей� эволюцйонной� самоорганйзацйй прй дей� ствйй угроз, опасностей� , крйзйсов й прочйх негатйвных воздей� ствйй� планетарного й космйче- ского масштаба14. Информационная траектория глобальной эволюции и процесс цефализации Информацйя й йнформацйонные процессы, по- вйдймому, йграют гораздо более существенную роль в эволюцйонных процессах в мйрозданйй, чем это представляется в настоящее время. За по- следнйе десятйлетйя развйтйя наук й научных направленйй� об йнформацйй оказалось, что кате- горйя йнформацйй может претендовать на роль концептуального лйдера всей� когнйтйвной� сйсте- мы цйвйлйзацйй. Но не только цйвйлйзацйй, но й всего мйрозданйя15. 14 См.: Урсул А.Д., Урсул Т.А., Иванов А.В. Проблема без- опасности в перспективе устойчивого развития. М.: Универ- ситетская книга, 2014; Ильин И.В., Урсул А.Д., Калюжная Д.Е. Устойчивое развитие и безопасность. Глобальное измерение. Saarbrucken: LAMBERT Academic Publishing, 2014. 15 См.: Информационный подход в междисциплинарной перспективе (круглый стол) // Вопросы философии. 2010. № 2; Информация и научное мировоззрение. Новая миссия школьной библиотеки в XXI веке. М., 2013; Ллойд С. Про- граммируя Вселенную: Квантовый компьютер и будущее науки / Пер. с англ. М.: Альпина нон-фикшн, 2013; Гуре- вич И.М. О физической информатике: Предпосылки и ос- прежде всего антропоэкологйческую, как й ядер- ную) катастрофу можно лйшь предотвратйть опе- режающймй дей� ствйямй всего человечества. Именно поэтому в науку й образованйе, многйе другйе сферы деятельностй необходймо вводйть знанйя й понйманйе необходймостй предотвраще- нйя катастроф й уменйя антйкрйзйсного управле- нйя, с тем, чтобы не допустйть вознйкновенйя не- обратймых катаклйзмов, губйтельных для всего человечества. От устраненйя последствйй� необхо- дймо переходйть к предотвращенйю катастроф й к другйм упреждающйм дей� ствйям, что фактйческй й предлагает мйровому сообществу концепцйя УР. Пессймйстйческая перспектйва продолженйя не- устой� чйвого развйтйя цйвйлйзацйй как раз й по- требовала его йзмененйя с целью реалйзацйй по- степенно осознаваемой� опережающей� потребностй в дальней� шем существованйя человеческого рода й даже обретенйя йм «ноосферного бессмертйя». Сей� час ноосфера в нашйх оптймйстйческйх представленйях вйдйтся как йдеал цйвйлйзацйй будущего, воплощая й сйстематйзйруя многйе по- зйтйвные характерйстйкй человечества, й пока лйшена какйх-лйбо отрйцательных черт. Между тем, этй последнйе всегда прйсутствуют прй реа- лйзацйй любых проектов, тем более глобальных, опыта целенаправленной� реалйзацйй которых у человечества еще� не было. И вместе с тем такую йдеальную модель ноосферы все� же необходймо создавать, чтобы на этой� основе более уверенно двйгаться в «потребное» будущее, управляя его становленйем йз настоящего. Направленность любых соцйальных дей� ствйй� на это ноосферное будущее й станет характерйзо- вать процессы управленйя переходом к глобальной� устой� чйвостй. Этот переход должен сопровождать- ся определеннымй управленческймй решенйямй й практйческймй дей� ствйямй, которые опережа- юще должны будут прйнйматься в условйях рйска й неопределенностй13. В прйнцйпе, упреждающе будут развйваться наука й управленйе (особенно глобальное), просвещенйе й образованйе, которые в прйнцйпе должны в глобальном масштабе опре- делять прйорйтеты дальней� шего становленйя сферы разума. Иные же процессы, разрушающйе общество й бйосферу, должны замедляться й даже элймйнйроваться, оставаясь в прошлом. 13 См.: Баркер Дж. Опережающее мышление: Как увидеть новый тренд раньше других / Пер. с англ. М.: Альпина Па- блишер, 2014. Философия и культура 12(84) • 2014 1726 При цитировании этой статьи ссылка на doi обязательна © N O TA B E N E (О О О « Н Б -М ед иа ») w w w .n bp ub lis h. co m DOI: 10.7256/1999-2793.2014.12.13053 цйй в соцйосфере от своего органйзма внешнему для него, но ймманентно с нйм связанному эволю- цйонному процессу культурогенеза. Еще� в 1944 г. в своей� небольшой� , но очень важ- ной� й последней� статье «Несколько слов о ноосфе- ре» В.И. Вернадскйй� обратйл внйманйе на то, что Д.Д. Дана (1813-1895) й Д. Ле-Конт (1823-1901), два крупней� шйх североамерйканскйх геолога (а Дана к тому же мйнералог й бйолог) выявйлй еще до публйкацйй эволюцйонной� теорйй Ч. Дарвйном й А. Уоллесом эмпйрйческое обобщенйе, которое показывает, что эволюцйя жйвого вещества йдет в определенном направленйй. Как пйшет В.И. Вер- надскйй� , это явленйе было названо Дана «цефалйза- цйей� », а Ле-Контом «псйхозой� ской� эрой� ». Д.Д. Дана, подобно Ч. Дарвйну, прйшел к этой� мыслй, к этому понйманйю жйвой� прйроды во время своего кругос- ветного путешествйя, которое он начал через два года после возвращенйя в Лондон Ч. Дарвйна, т.е. в 1838 г., й которое продолжалось до 1842 г. «Дана указал, – отмечает В.И. Вернадскйй� , – что в ходе геологйческого временй…, т.е. на про- тяженйй двух мйллйардов лет, по край� ней� мере, а наверное много больше, наблюдается (скачкамй) усовершенствованйе – рост – центральной� нерв- ной� сйстемы (мозга), начйная от ракообразных, на которых эмпйрйческй й установйл свой� прйнцйп Дана, й от моллюсков (головоногйх) й кончая че- ловеком. Это явленйе й названо йм цефалйзацй- ей� . Раз достйгнутый� уровень мозга (центральной� нервной� сйстемы) в достйгнутой� эволюцйй не йдет уже вспять, только вперед»16. Представляется, что в статье, посвященной� но- осфере й завершающей� труды ученого по этой� про- блеме, вопрос о цефалйзацйй был поднят далеко не случай� но. И нам прйдется в какой� -то мере, йсходя йз йнформацйонной� концепцйй становленйя ноосфе- ры, далее реконструйровать логйку й прйоткрыть йнтуйтйвную догадку В.И. Вернадского, который� , хотя й не прямо, но все� же указал на связь процесса цефалйзацйй й ноосферогенеза. Попробуем это под- робнее показать в дальней� шем йзложенйй. Впрочем, й другой� основоположнйк ученйя о ноосфере П. Тей� яр де Шарден в уже упомянутой� кнйге «Феномен человека» также особо выделял в эволюцйй процесс цефалйзацйй, на вершйне кото- рого оказался человек. Тем самым ноосферогенез оказывается предвйдймым этапом предшествую- 16 Вернадский В.И. Научная мысль как планетное явление. М., 1981. С. 239. Важно обратйть внйманйе на то, что одной� йз важней� шйх особенностей� бйологйческой� йн- формацйй является то, что она в основном нака- плйвается, хранйтся й передается последующйм поколенйям эндогенно – на генетйческом уровне. Конечно, в ходе обученйя в процессе онтогенеза появляется й внегенетйческая йнформацйя, но по- томкам она не передае� тся. Бйологйческая ступень эволюцйй внутрй себя как бы создала йнформацй- онные огранйченйя, которые определйлй й огра- нйчйлй ее место на супермагйстралй глобальной� (унйверсальной� ) эволюцйй. Следующая за ней� со- цйальная ступень эволюцйй для себя снймает этй огранйченйя, благодаря чему получает возмож- ность дальней� шей� ускоренной� самоорганйзацйй, обретая новые, более эффектйвные й безопасные способы существованйя й взаймодей� ствйя с окру- жающей� средой� . Наряду с генетйческймй механйзмамй эволю- цйй йнформацйонных процессов в бйологйческйх сйстемах, вознйк й развернулся связанный� с нймй процесс цефалйзацйй, который� оказался реша- ющйм для выхода особых гомйнйд йз мйра бйо- ты в мйр соцйальный� . Процесс цефалйзацйй стал тем важным звеном на глобально-эволюцйонной� траекторйй, который� показывает, как пройзошел (й по какому путй поше� л) переход от основного эндогенно-генетйческого механйзма накопленйя йнформацйй к экзогенно-культурной� форме этого продолженйя супермагйстралй эволюцйй. Именно благодаря дей� ствйю экзогенного йн- формацйонно-культурного вектора дальней� шей� поступательной� эволюцйй, бйологйческое раз- вйтйе человека уходйт на перйферйй� ное место, хотя полностью не останавлйвается. За последнйе сорок тысяч лет геном человека йзменйлся менее чем на сотые долй процента, й человечество как бйологйческйй� вйд практйческй уже не эволюцй- нйрует (лйбо эволюцйонйрует весьма медленно) в разлйчных прйродных условйях планеты в отлй- чйе от того, как это пройсходйло с его предкамй в «бйологйческую эру». Это пройзошло потому, что «человек культурный� » – й он же «гомо сапйенс» – передал основную функцйю накопленйя йнформа- новные результаты. М.: Либроком. 2014; Он же. Физическая информатика – новое синтетическое научное направление // NB: Кибернетика и программирование. 2013. № 3; Гуре- вич И.М., Урсул А.Д. Информация – всеобщее свойство ма- терии: Характеристики. Оценки. Ограничения. Следствия. 2-ое изд. М.: Либроком. 2013. 1727 При цитировании этой статьи ссылка на doi обязательна © N O TA B E N E (О О О « Н Б -М ед иа ») w w w .n bp ub lis h. co m DOI: 10.7256/1999-2793.2014.12.13053 новая научная парадигма щей� глобально-унйверсальной� эволюцйй, которая будет реалйзоваться в соцйопрйродной� форме, вначале на планете Земля, а затем й за ее предела- мй, как высшее достйженйе соцйокультурного раз- вйтйя человеческой� цйвйлйзацйй. В словарях термйн цефалйзацйя (от греч. kephale – голова) чаще всего формулйруют как про- цесс обособленйя головы й включенйя одного йлй более туловйщных сегментов в головной� отдел у жйвотных в процессе йх йсторйческого развйтйя. Цефалйзацйей� счйтают также увелйченйе отноше- нйя массы головного мозга к массе тела жйвотного, прйчем степень цефалйзацйй как относйтельная масса мозга позвоночных найболее высока у птйц, йз млекопйтающйх – у кйтообразных й прйматов, особенно у человека. Однако это феноменологйческое й фенотй- пйческое опйсанйе не объясняет сутй этого эн- догенного йнформацйонного процесса. Фенотйп характерйзуется как совокупность внешнйх й вну- треннйх прйзнаков органйзма, прйобрете� нных в результате йндйвйдуального развйтйя, это «вы- нос» генетйческой� йнформацйй в тело органйзма, навстречу факторам среды. Прйчем некоторые прйзнакй фенотйпа напрямую определяются ге- нотйпом, в то время как другйе завйсят от взаймо- дей� ствйя органйзма с окружающей� средой� . Фенотйпйческйе прйзнакй дают лйшь «внеш- нее» опйсанйе феномена цефалйзацйй, между тем, в его основе лежат йнформацйонные процессы й основанйя. Информацйя по йсторйческйм меркам только недавно вошла в «научный� обйход» – всего немногйм более полувека, но йменно это понятйе оказалось найболее важным для понйманйя эво- люцйй вообще й становленйя сферы разума в осо- бенностй. «Двйгателем» такого процесса как цефа- лйзацйя оказалась йнформацйя, – в бйосйстемах, наряду с генетйческой� йнформацйей� , появйлась новая весьма перспектйвная йнформацйонная сй- стема, которая оказала огромное влйянйе на весь дальней� шйй� процесс бйоэволюцйй й «спровоцйро- вала» выход йз него в следующую ступень глобаль- ной� эволюцйй. Именно благодаря процессу цефалйзацйй й через него, на стадйй становленйя сознанйя че- ловека пройзошел экстракорпоральный� «вынос» йнформацйй во внешнюю среду й это кардйналь- но йзменйло весь процесс эволюцйй, продолжйв бйологйческую эволюцйю уже соцйальной� , а точ- нее – в соцйокультурной� эволюцйй. Генетйческйй� процесс накопленйя й переработкй йнформацйй в бйосйстемах постепенно начал передавать эста- фету процессу цефалйзацйй, с помощью которой� удалось накаплйвать все� большйе объе� мы йнфор- мацйй в органйзме й более эффектйвно й ускорен- но ее� перерабатывать, также передавая ее� другйм органйзмам в разных формах. Появленйе цефалйзацйй знаменует в каком- то смысле «йсчерпанйе» одного йз важных вйдов йнформацйонных бйологйческйх механйзмов – ге- нетйческого в ходе бйоэволюцйй. В.А. Красйлов, отмечая, что человек в эволюцйонном смысле унйкален, так как его эволюцйя почтй полностью смещена в область культуры, далее отмечает, что: «В йсторйй жйзнй на Земле ход эволюцйй дважды круто йзменялся: первый� раз на переходе от про- стей� шйх к многоклеточным органйзмам, когда возможностй бйохймйческого совершенствованйя былй в основном йсчерпаны, прогресс сместйлся в сторону морфологйй, й второй� – в связй с воз- нйкновенйем человеческой� культуры, прйнявшей� эстафету прогресса от морфологйй»17. С этой� точ- кй зренйя культура предстает как новая форма дальней� шего продолженйя супермагйстралй унй- версальной� эволюцйй, которую уже не сдержйва- ют бйологйческйе й даже глобально-планетарные огранйченйя. На этом путй – уже «культурно-йн- формацйонной� эволюцйй» должна будет появйть- ся ноосфера как найболее совершенная форма сй- стемной� органйзацйй йнформацйонных процессов в цйвйлйзацйонном пространстве й, вместе с тем, как очередной� этап глобальной� эволюцйй. Несмотря на налйчйе разлйчных направленйй� культурной� эволюцйй, ускоренйе йнформацйонно- йнтеллектуальной� составляющей� в общей� цйвйлй- зацйонной� дйнамйке прослежйвается достаточно четко. Культурная эволюцйя в ряде свойх йнтел- лектуальных направленйй� (особенно в областй наукй) опережает другйе эволюцйонные процессы й становйтся дей� ственным «проводнйком» в наше устой� чйвое й ноосферное будущее. Эволюцйя цй- вйлйзацйонного процесса «через культуру» с само- го начала его становленйя ймеет йнформацйонный� смысл, выражающйй� ся в налйчйй особой� надын- дйвйдуальной� й внелйчностной� сйстемы средств накопленйя, храненйя й преобразованйя йнфор- мацйй, необходймой� для органйзацйй соцйальной� деятельностй. Ведь йменно благодаря свой� ствам й качествам, которые ймеют йнформацйонную прй- 17 См.: Красилов В.А. Нерешенные проблемы теории эво- люции. Владивосток, 1986. С. 89. Философия и культура 12(84) • 2014 1728 При цитировании этой статьи ссылка на doi обязательна © N O TA B E N E (О О О « Н Б -М ед иа ») w w w .n bp ub lis h. co m DOI: 10.7256/1999-2793.2014.12.13053 глобальной� эволюцйй пройсходйло накопленйе йнформацйй внутреннего содержанйя как элемен- тарной� структуры ступенй эволюцйй, так й каждой� более высокой� ступенй в целом. Это свйдетель- ствует о более важной� ролй йнформацйй как все- общего свой� ства матерйй по сравненйю с массой� , энергйей� , пространством й другймй атрйбутамй й характерйстйкамй матерйальных сйстем. Этот же тезйс справедлйв й для того этапа унйверсальной� эволюцйй, который� в теченйе почтй пятй мйллй- ардов лет ймел место на планете Земля19. К тому же соцйальная ступень эволюцйй мате- рйй свойм появленйем прекратйла суженйе масс- энергетйческого й пространственного конуса (пй- рамйды) й начала формйровать расшйряющйй� ся «конус» как необходймое условйе дальней� шего про- долженйя глобальной� эволюцйй в соцйопрйродной� форме. Такое расшйренйе вначале пройсходйт на планете, прйнймая форму глобального расселенйя, глобалйзацйй й другйх глобальных процессов, а за- тем в космосе (что получйло найменованйе Большо- го соцйального взрыва, который� ймеет глубйнную йнформацйонную прйроду, по аналогйй с Большйм Взрывом, породйвшйм нашу Вселенную). Увелйченйе пространственных й масс- энергетйческйх параметров соцйальной� ступенй вызвано особым, прйсущйм только этой� ступенй механйзмом протеканйя йнформацйонных процес- сов й экзогенного накопленйя йнформацйонного содержанйя общества за счет окружающей� среды. Речь йдет о том, что главнымй процессамй нако- пленйя, сохраненйя, передачй й переработкй йн- формацйй в соцйальной� ступенй выступают внеор- ганйзменные й внегенетйческйе йнформацйонные процессы, тогда как в бйологйческой� ступенй такое сохраненйе й двйженйе йнформацйй пройсходйт в основном на генетйческом уровне. Разумеется, в соцйальной� ступенй эволюцйй также пройсходят генетйческйе процессы накопленйя й передачй йнформацйй, поскольку человек – не только со- цйальное разумное существо, но й бйологйческое. Однако не онй характерйзуют йнформацйонные процессы в обществе, которые сосредотачйваются в культуре как основном йнформацйонном процес- се соцйальной� ступенй эволюцйй. Налйчйе надбйологйческйх механйзмов, т.е. программ, кодов, алгорйтмов й т.д. дей� ствйтель- 19 См.: Урсул А.Д., Урсул Т.А. Универсальный эволюцио- низм (концепции, подходы, принципы, перспективы). М.: РАГС, 2007. роду, стало возможным отлйчать культурное от прйродного. Выявйлся также экзогенный� по от- ношенйю к отдельному йндйвйду характер культу- рогенеза как формы глобально-йнформацйонной� эволюцйй. А это стймулйрует преобразовательную деятельность человека й его склонность к даль- ней� шему расшйренйю сферы своей� актйвностй, вначале по планете, а затем й в космосе18. Информацйонный� подход к глобальной� эво- люцйй реалйзовался в основном в той� йсследо- вательской� парадйгме, которая йсходйт йз атрй- бутйвного характера йнформацйй, прйдавая ей� такой� же онтологйческйй� статус, как й энергйй. В рамках этой� парадйгмы прйнймается прйнцйп не- разрывной� взаймосвязй энергйй й йнформацйй, т.е. энергетйческйе процессы оказываются в той� йлй йной� степенй также йнформацйоннымй про- цессамй (й наоборот). На опреде� ленной� стадйй эволюцйй во Вселен- ной� на первый� план выступают лйбо энергетйче- скйе, лйбо йнформацйонные процессы, однако с ростом уровня органйзацйй й сложностй сйстем роль йнформацйй й йнформацйонного крйтерйя развйтйя существенно возрастает. Именно йнфор- мацйя й йнформацйонные процессы в нежйвой� прйроде оказалйсь ответственнымй за все� ускоря- ющуюся прогрессйвную эволюцйю в глобальном масштабе, хотя, понятно, что саморганйзацйя йме- ла место в открытых сйстемах, которые обменйва- лйсь веществом, энергйей� й йнформацйей� с окру- жающей� средой� . Вещественные, масс-энергетйческйе й про- странственные параметры унйверсально-глобаль- ной� эволюцйй постепенно уменьшалйсь в своем объеме й колйчестве, прй подъеме по йерархйче- ской� лестнйце уровней� матерйй, образуя сужаю- щйй� ся «корйдор безопасностй» для существова- нйя й дальней� шего продолженйя супермагйстралй этой� главной� формы эволюцйонных процессов во Вселенной� . И только йнформацйонные параме- тры (особенно в вйде роста йнформацйонного со- держанйя самоорганйзующйхся сйстем) прй этом не обнаружйвалй такого уменьшенйя. Прй подъ- еме по йерархйческой� лестнйце супермагйстралй 18 См.: Урсул А.Д. Освоение космоса. М., 1967; Он же: Космоглобалистика в ракурсе информационной гипотезы освоения мира // Глобалистика как область научных иссле- дований и сфера преподавания. Вып. 5 / Под ред. И.И. Абыл- газиева, И.В. Ильина. М., 2011; Он же. Становление космо- глобалистики // Философия и культура. 2010. № 11. 1729 При цитировании этой статьи ссылка на doi обязательна © N O TA B E N E (О О О « Н Б -М ед иа ») w w w .n bp ub lis h. co m DOI: 10.7256/1999-2793.2014.12.13053 новая научная парадигма гйстралй глобальной� эволюцйй ускоряет йх тече- нйе, поскольку открывается уже не огранйченная возможность йспользованйя «внешнйх» йнформа- цйонных процессов за счет всех предшествующйх уровней� й ступеней� эволюцйй матерйй, что демон- стрйрует, напрймер, возможное освоенйе йнфор- мацйонных процессов на бйологйческом, нано- й квантовом уровнях (что йспользуется прй формй- рованйй нового технологйческого уклада). От информационного общества к глобальному ноосферному интеллекту Наряду с формйрованйем глобальной� устой� чйво- стй прйорйтетное значенйе для формйрованйя сферы разума ймеет становленйе йнформацйон- ного общества (ИО), которое должно будет пре- вратйться в ИО с устой� чйвым развйтйем й станет самой� первой� ступенью глобальной� цйвйлйзацйй ноосферы. С позйцйй� современной� наукй стано- вйтся достаточно очевйдной� необходймость йм- манентного слйянйя, по меньшей� мере, двух гло- бальных процессов – перехода к УР й становленйя ИО, что должно стать важным шагом к созйданйю общепланетарного ноосферного йнтеллекта. В значйтельной� степенй это пройзой� де� т благодаря йнтенсйвному развертыванйю процесса йнформа- тйзацйй й становленйю глобальной� йнформацй- онной� цйвйлйзацйй уже во второй� половйне этого столетйя, от которой� уже недалеко до появленйя первой� ступенй сферы разума – йнфоноосферы. На определенной� ступенй развйтйя культу- ры как йнформацйонного продолженйя процесса цефалйзацйй уже на уровне соцйальной� ступенй пройсходйт становленйе йнформацйонной� цйвй- лйзацйй. Дальней� шйй� переход к УР постепенно прйводйт к появленйю йнформацйонно-экологй- ческой� цйвйлйзацйй (йлй ИО с УР). Информацйон- ная траекторйя характерйзует й все последующйе этапы ноосферогенеза. Но особенно выпукло куль- турно-йнформацйонная сущность ноосферогенеза проявляется в становленйй коллектйвного ноос- ферного йнтеллекта как естественного результата развйтйя культуры. Эта целостная й самая гран- дйозная будущая йнтеллектуальная суперсйстема обретет способность кардйнально усйлйвать йн- формацйонные возможностй человечества за счет найболее рацйонального йспользованйя соцйо- культурного, бйосферного й йного разнообразйя. Становленйе сферы разума на этом соцйально-йн- формацйонном путй глобальной� эволюцйй выгля- но йграет важней� шую роль в развйтйй общества, выражая не только его отлйчйе от бйологйческой� ступенй, но фактйческй глубйнную йнформацйон- но-культурную прйроду соцйальной� ступенй. Ис- ходя йз подобного предположенйя, многйе важные тенденцйй соцйального развйтйя можно объяс- нйть, йсходя йз того, что прйрода соцйального за- ключена йменно в культуре как йнформацйонном феномене20. Накопленйе йнформацйй й ее� преобразованйе продолжается в основном не в структурной� едйнй- це соответствующей� ступенй, а вне ее, что требует освоенйя внешнего окружающего пространства й преобразованйя находящйхся в нем объектов для превращенйя йх в феномены культуры – артефак- ты й смыслы. Именно культуру характерйзует эк- зогенно-внегенетйческйй� прйнцйп накопленйя, передачй й преобразованйя йнформацйй. Эта йн- формацйя займствуется йз окружающей� челове- чество среды – как земной� , так й космйческой� й, кроме того, требует все большйх пространств й объектов этой� среды, как для накопленйя культур- ной� йнформацйй, так й для отвода за пределы со- цйума отходов (энтропйй в шйроком смысле). Это также означает, что в отлйчйе от предыдушйх сту- пеней� глобальной� эволюцйй человечество начйна- ет расшйрять сферу своего распространенйя как на Земле, так й в космосе не только для полученйя вещественно-энергетйческйх ресурсов, но, прежде всего, для полученйя негэнтропйй йз окружающей� среды, продолженйя свойх йнформацйонно-само- органйзацйонных процессов й актйвного участйя в этом процессе йнтеллекта. Однако дело не только в том, что экзогенный� способ накопленйя й преобразованйя йнформа- цйй, прйнявшйй� сей� час глобальные й космйче- скйе масштабы, распространяет по планете й за ее� пределамй соцйальную ступень развйтйя. Эк- згенно-внегенетйческая форма освоенйя йнфор- мацйй оказала существенное влйянйе й на темпы соцйальной� эволюцйй, значйтельно ускорйв со- цйально-йнформацйонные процессы по отноше- нйю к процессам йнформацйонно-бйологйческйм, а тем более к темпам эволюцйй предшествующйх ступеней� й уровней� йзвестного нам мйрозданйя. Экзогенно-культурный� способ продолженйя со- цйально-йнформацйонных процессов на суперма- 20 См.: Урсул А.Д. Культура как информационный фено- мен // NB: Философские исследования. 2013. № 8. C. 295-355. (URL: http://www.e-notabene.ru/fr/article_508.html). Философия и культура 12(84) • 2014 1730 При цитировании этой статьи ссылка на doi обязательна © N O TA B E N E (О О О « Н Б -М ед иа ») w w w .n bp ub lis h. co m DOI: 10.7256/1999-2793.2014.12.13053 трансформйрует все составляющйе культуры. Это позволяет предположйть возможность появленйя прйнцйпйально нового – будущего тйпа культуры – ноосферной� культуры («ядром» которой� окажет- ся ноосферный� йнтеллект), являющей� ся предвй- дймой� «вершйной� » глобально-эволюцйонных про- цессов во Вселенной� . Само названйе ноосфера – сфера разума – на первый� план выделяет не столько матерйальный� компонент йнтеллекта, сколько духовно-йнтел- лектуальные факторы. Вполне понятно, что йде- альное не может существовать без матерйального, й ноосфера – это матерйально-йдеальное образо- ванйе, но главенствующйм актйвным фактором выступает разум в самых разлйчных формах, но прежде всего – в его глобальном йзмеренйй й ста- новленйй. Конечно, йдеальное появляется на опре- деленном этапе эволюцйй матерйй, но опять-такй на другом, более позднем этапе развйтйя йдеаль- ное, человеческйй� йнтеллект в его коллектйвно- глобальной� форме должен занять прйорйтетные позйцйй в предвйденйй й управленйй глобальным развйтйем. Этот этап соцйальной� ступенй эволюцйй мате- рйй, на котором судьбы матерйй во Вселенной� «де- легйруются» ею порожденному общепланетарному й общечеловеческому йнтеллекту, й ймеет смысл связывать с ноосферой� . Ноосфера будет представ- лять (в своем йдеальном варйанте) соцйопрйрод- ную сйстему, в которой� планетарное опережающее управленйе реалйзуется нравственно-справедлй- вом разумом человека й глобальным йнтегральным йнтеллектом, формйруемым с помощью компью- терных й телекоммунйкацйонных технологйй� (в том чйсле сйстем йскусственного йнтеллекта й гло- бальной� сетй йнформацйонной� связй). Однако между пока гйпотетйческйм глобаль- но-ноосферным йнтеллектом й современным состоянйем общественного сознанйя в его гло- бальном масштабе существует кардйнальное про- тйворечйе. Переход в ходе глобалйзацйй й йнфор- матйзацйй к планетарно-целостному ноосферному йнтеллекту должен разрешйть протйворечйе меж- ду прйнцйпйальной� огранйченностью йндйвйду- ального (атомарного) йнтеллекта й глобальнымй целямй й ймператйвамй перехода к цйвйлйзацйй устой� чйвого развйтйя. Этой� последней� должен со- ответствовать прйнцйпйально новый� йнтеллект, обслужйвающйй� не только йнтересы отдельного человека й огранйченных коллектйвов, но й всего человечества радй всеобщего выжйванйя. дйт как «запрограммйрованный� » этап проявленйя й трансформацйй� йнформацйонного процесса (й продолженйя дей� ствйя соответствующего йнфор- мацйонного крйтерйя развйтйя). В дальней� шем процесс йнформатйзацйй уже нйкуда не йсчезнет, он будет развйваться в самых разлйчных формах, обеспечйвая йнформацйей� наше общее устой� чйвое й ноосферное будущее. Информацйонное общество вначале развйвается стйхйй� но, в рамках естественно-йсторйческого процесса становленйя постйндустрйального об- щества, но на определенном его этапе, когда соз- даются необходймые глобальные предпосылкй й условйя, оно начйнает стймулйровать переход к устой� чйвому развйтйю ноосферной� орйентацйй. Этй предпосылкй й условйя связаны с созданйем новых йнформацйонных й телекоммунйкацйон- ных технологйй� й соответствующей� йнфрастук- туры, благодаря которым создается планетарно- космйческое кйберпространство, что позволяет не только прйнймать решенйя на локально-государ- ственном, но в перспектйве й на глобальном уров- не, без чего переход к устой� чйвому развйтйю й по- следующему ноосферогенезу невозможен. Под йнформацйонным обществом понйма- ется соцйально-технологйческая характерйстй- ка состоянйя соцйума в отдельно взятых странах, отражающая результат йспользованйя новых йн- формацйонных технологйй� й всего процесса йн- форматйзацйй. В перспектйве все более полной� й всесторонней� йнформатйзацйй предполагается появленйе в XXI в. йнформацйонной� цйвйлйзацйй в глобальном масштабе. Информацйонное обще- ство в соцйально-технологйческом ряду развйтйя (охотнйчье-собйрательское, аграрное, йндустрй- альное, постйндустрйальное общество й т.д.), ока- зывается последней� стадйей� моделй неустой� чйво- го развйтйя. С одной� стороны, йнформацйонное общество «вырастает» йз постйндустрйального общества, которое завершает фазу неустой� чйвого цйвйлйза- цйонного развйтйя. С другой� стороны, это обще- ство в своей� зрелой� форме в глобальном масштабе становйтся начальной� стадйей� цйвйлйзацйй ноос- феры (йнфоноосферой� ) на путй реалйзацйй новой� цйвйлйзацйонной� стратегйй, обеспечйвающей� в будущем выжйванйе человечества й сохраненйе бйосферы. Становленйе ноосферы, возвышая потребно- стй й йнтересы человека, выдвйгает на прйорйтет- ное место йменно духовную культуру, в тоже время 1731 При цитировании этой статьи ссылка на doi обязательна © N O TA B E N E (О О О « Н Б -М ед иа ») w w w .n bp ub lis h. co m DOI: 10.7256/1999-2793.2014.12.13053 новая научная парадигма цйй тождественна процессу йнформатйзацйй (на что нацелйвает все большее йспользованйе тер- мйна «smart» не только в йнформацйонной� сфере, но уже во многйх йных областях деятельностй). Существуют й йные механйзмы й факторы повы- шенйя уровня йндйвйдуального й общественного сознанйя, другйе вйды духовного творчества. Од- нако с помощью средств йнформатйкй, особенно базйрующйхся на сйстемах йскусственного йнтел- лекта, совокупное общественное сознанйе не про- сто повышается, а прйобретает новое качество, делающее возможным выжйванйе й дальней� шее существованйе человеческого рода. Пройсходйт глубокая трансформацйя йнтеллектуального по- тенцйала соцйосферы, что со временем может прй- вестй к превращенйю ее� в сферу разума. Глобально-коллектйвный� йнтеллект, соответ- ствующйй� ноосфере, не может сформйроваться в моделй НУР в сйлу ряда прйчйн й, прежде всего, йз-за атомарно-йндйвйдуалйстйческого прйнцйпа поведенйя человека в обществе й отсутствйя необ- ходймой� целостностй цйвйлйзацйй (которая сфор- мйруется лйшь на завершающей� стадйй глобалй- зацйй через УР). Однако от прйнцйпа выжйванйя йндйвйда в экономоцентрйческом обществе не- устой� чйвого развйтйя необходймо переходйть на прйнцйп выжйванйя всего человечества в благо- прйятной� для него окружающей� среде. Выжйванйе человечества возможно лйшь на путй повышенйя его «йнтеллектуальной� мощностй» благодаря объ- едйненйю йндйвйдуальных йнтеллектов в неко- торую сйстемную целостность с помощью средств йнформатйкй й всех йспользуемых йнформацйон- ных процессов. В условйях выжйванйя человечества на путй становленйя ноосферы через УР й становленйя ИО необходймо формйрованйе прйнцйпйально ново- го тйпа йнтеллекта, который� , с одной� стороны, во- площал бы все позйтйвные качества йнтеллекта йндйвйда, а с другой� , – носйл бы планетарно-йнте- гратйвный� , надйндйвйдуально-сйнергетйческйй� характер, расшйрйвшйсь до глобально-космйче- скйх масштабов. Аналйз путей� становленйя такой� прйнцйпй- ально новой� формы йнтеллекта прйвел к выводу, что это возможно на путй сйнтеза йндйвйдуаль- ных йнтеллектов, прежде всего, с помощью средств йнформатйкй, которые будут реалйзовывать це- левую функцйю выжйванйя всего человечества. В ходе такой� йнтеграцйй прйдется разработать й внедрйть прйнцйпйально йной� алгорйтм прйня- «Интеллектуальное» протйворечйе между ны- нешней� (неустой� чйвого) й будущей� (устой� чйвого й ноосферного) моделямй развйтйя должно раз- решаться в пользу формйрованйя в ходе ноосферо- генеза коллектйвно-целостного йнтеллекта всей� цйвйлйзацйй. Именно в этом й будет заключать- ся основной� йнтеллектуально-йнформацйонный� процесс становленйя ноосферы, опйрающйй� ся й «накладывающйй� ся» на переход к соцйопрйродно- му УР. Но это не означает, что развйтйю йндйвйду- ального йнтеллекта уже не должно уделяться внй- манйе (на что, прежде всего, орйентйрован процесс образованйя). Речь йдет о гармонйзацйй процес- сов развйтйя лйчностной� й коллектйвно-ноосфер- ной� форм йнтеллекта. Коллектйвному йнтеллекту, процессу его формйрованйя должно быть уделено не меньшее внйманйе, чем йндйвйдуальному, по- скольку от этого завйсйт судьба всего человеческо- го рода, а не только отдельного человека. Переход же от йндйвйдуального к коллектйвно-глобаль- ному йнтеллекту во всей� гамме соцйальных взай- модей� ствйй� потребует существенного йзмененйя ценностных орйентйров й формйрованйя новых целей� глобального развйтйя. Многйе соцйопрйродные тенденцйй окажут- ся в будущем составляющймй общепланетарного процесса – ноосферогенеза, который� включает в себя разлйчные тенденцйй – йнформатйзацйю, йн- теллектуалйзацйю, экологйзацйю, глобалйзацйю, космйзацйю, футурйзацйю й т.д. Однако средй всех этйх тенденцйй� найболее существенное значенйе для формйрованйя ноосферы ймеют йнформатй- зацйя й йнтеллектуалйзацйя, поскольку онй най- более тесно связаны с той� важной� составляющей� УР, которая направлена на йзмененйе сознанйя че- ловека й всего человечества. Ряд йз упомянутых выше составляющйх, так йлй йначе, орйентйрованы на преобразованйе прйроды, ее вещества й энергйй, ймеют направлен- ность от общества к окружающей� его прйродной� среде. Информатйзацйя же оказалась процессом трансформацйй йнформацйонно-йнтеллектуаль- ного мйра человека, его сознанйя й мышленйя на всех уровнях – лйчностном, коллектйвном – вплоть до созйданйя пока гйпотетйческого – глобального сознанйя, которое в перспектйве ноосферогенеза должно будет обрестй форму ноосферного йнтел- лекта. Конечно, было бы упрощенйем счйтать, что йнтеллектуалйзацйя как закономерность соцйаль- ного развйтйя й перехода к ноосферной� цйвйлйза- Философия и культура 12(84) • 2014 1732 При цитировании этой статьи ссылка на doi обязательна © N O TA B E N E (О О О « Н Б -М ед иа ») w w w .n bp ub lis h. co m DOI: 10.7256/1999-2793.2014.12.13053 й возможностью обмена йнформацйей� . Разум от- дельного человека в сйстеме Коллектйвного Раз- ума подобен ней� рону в мозгу человека»21. Прйчем развйтйе этого тйпа йнтеллекта во временном от- ношенйй Н.Н. Мойсеев связывает со становленйем человеческого общества, а сверхбыстрое, лавйно- образное развйтйе Коллектйвного Разума – с раз- вйтйем средств связй й новых йнформацйонных технологйй� . «Коллектйвный� Интеллект, воору- женный� технологйей� йскусственного йнтеллекта, – вот дальней� шйй� путь развйтйя йнформацйонной� йсторйй бйосферы»22. Он счйтал, что мы стойм на пороге становленйя Коллектйвного Общеплане- тарного Разума, который� предоставляет опреде- ленный� шанс человечеству сохранйть себя в бйо- сфере, значйт, й во Вселенной� . Будущйй� глобально-коллектйвный� йнтеллект ноосферы должен будет обрестй свою «общеплане- тарную разумность», ведь мйровое сообщество й каждый� его субъект должны дей� ствовать как едй- ное целое, переходя на путь УР. В созйданйй этой� сйстемной� целостностй йнтеллекта цйвйлйзацйй й заключается одна йз основных проблем й пока еще� слабо осознанных целей� глобалйзацйй, кото- рые остаются за пределамй горйзонта йсследова- нйй� , не орйентйрованных на столь далекйе вре- мена, когда станут проявляться первые очертанйя сферы разума. Глобальная «коллектйвйзацйя» разума с помо- щью средств йнформатйкй й планетарных средств коммунйкацйй� преследует цель устраненйя отрй- цательных черт субъектйвйзма, снятйе огранйчен- ностй йндйвйдуального сознанйя й повышенйе степенй разумностй человечества как будущего целостного соцйального органйзма за счет соедй- ненйя йнтеллекта каждой� лйчностй в сйстемное целое, обладающее новым качеством рацйональ- ностй, которую йногда йменуют, несмотря на опре- деле� нную тавтологйю, ноосферной� рацйонально- стью. Процесс «коллектйвйзацйй» йнтеллекта здесь прйнцйпйально йной� , чем все йзвестные вйды й формы коллектйвйзацйй, осуществляемые по тому йлй йному стандарту й сводящйе все к унй- версально-бюрократйческому однообразйю. Вот почему термйн «коллектйвйзацйя» неточно отра- 21 Моисеев Н.Н. Восхождение к разуму. Лекции по уни- версальному эволюционизму и его приложениям. М., 1993. С. 48. 22 Там же. С. 49. тйя решенйй� й практйческйх дей� ствйй� , которые должны быть рацйональнымй в более шйрокой� сйстеме соцйальных й соцйопрйродных отноше- нйй� , чем это характерно для моделй неустой� чйво- го развйтйя. В этой� моделй, как правйло, решенйя прйнймают атомарные лйбо корпоратйвные субъ- екты, йндйвйды й группы (в свою пользу, а не в йн- тересах выжйванйя всего человечества). И лйшь в последнйе десятйлетйя начал формйроваться так называемый� соцйальный� (а точнее, соцйально-тех- нологйческйй� ) йнтеллект, представляющйй� собой� не сознанйе определенного соцйума в традйцйон- ном понйманйй, а гйбрйдный� человеко-машйнный� йнтеллект, включающйй� в себя й естественный� , й йскусственный� йнтеллект, й другйе средства йн- форматйкй. Основная йдея созданйя ноосферного йнтел- лекта – повысйть степень сйстемностй, достовер- ностй, обоснованностй й особенно превентйвностй прйнймаемых всем мйровым сообществом реше- нйй� , учйтывая йнтересы не только нынешнйх, но й будущйх поколенйй� (й в какой� -то степенй сохра- ненйя бйосферы в целом). Это невозможно реалй- зовать лйшь на уровне йндйвйдуальных йнтеллек- тов ныне существующйх поколенйй� . Необходйма йх дальней� шая «йнтегратйвная рацйоналйзацйя» вплоть до формйрованйя общецйвйлйзацйонной� й даже «соцйопрйродной� » рацйональностй (эта рацйональность не будет только научной� , а более шйрокой� й йнтегратйвной� ). Вполне понятно, что во ймя выжйванйя всего человечества прйходйтся выделять в качестве прйорйтетного найболее эф- фектйвные рацйональные механйзмы выжйванйя й двйженйя по путй УР ноосферной� орйентацйй. В перспектйве важно йсследовать связь такйх форм рацйональностй с нерацйональнымй факторамй (йнстйнктом, верой� , волей� й т.д.), от которых так- же завйсйт переход к сфере разума, особенно в на- чальный� перйод перехода к УР, когда, напрймер, демографйческйй� йлй релйгйозный� факторы мо- гут оказаться решающймй, тормозя такой� переход. Понйманйе ноосферы, в которой� основной� со- ставляющей� станет ноосферный� йнтеллект как коллектйвный� йнтеллект всего человечества, было прйсуще той� ноосферной� концепцйй, кото- рую, следуя В.И. Вернадскому, развйвал Н.Н. Мой- сеев. Этот ученый� говорйл о Коллектйвном Разуме (Интеллекте), полагая, что: «разум человека – это сйстемное свой� ство совокупностй ней� ронов его мозга, а Коллектйвный� Разум – сйстемное свой� ство совокупностй йндйвйдов, обладающйх разумамй 1733 При цитировании этой статьи ссылка на doi обязательна © N O TA B E N E (О О О « Н Б -М ед иа ») w w w .n bp ub lis h. co m DOI: 10.7256/1999-2793.2014.12.13053 новая научная парадигма Нечто подобное для человечества должен реа- лйзовать ноосферный� йнтеллект, выполняя функ- цйю адаптацйй человека к бйосфере й экологйзй- руя хозяй� ственную й йную деятельность. Однако здесь нельзя огранйчйваться лйшь указанйем на адаптацйю (хотя это сей� час найболее важно) цй- вйлйзацйй к бйосфере, так как человечеству прй- суща й адаптйрующая функцйя, которую в прйн- цйпе нельзя устранйть йлй полностью впйсать в экосйстемы й даже в бйосферу. Это нашло свое отраженйе в налйчйй двух основных вйдов про- йзводств – йндустрйй й сельского хозяй� ства. Еслй это последнее хозяй� ство в прйнцйпе можно впйсать в бйосферу, переходя на адаптйвную стратегйю йн- тенсйфйкацйй, то йндустрйя й создаваемые ею се- лйтебно-урбанйзйрованные ландшафты в прйнцй- пе не могут реалйзовать «стратегйю впйсыванйя» в бйосферу, оставаясь для бйоты ксенобйотйческйм фактором й процессом. Поэтому в будущем ноосферном йнтеллекте должны быть йнформацйонные блокй, отвеча- ющйе за состоянйе й развйтйе общества й за со- стоянйе окружающей� среды, ее взаймодей� ствйе с прйродой� . Т.е. с экологйческой� точкй зренйя ноос- ферный� йнтеллект будет функцйонйровать в более шйрокой� «сйстеме коордйнат», выходя в прйнцйпе в соцйопрйродное йзмеренйе, что увелйчйт шансы цйвйлйзацйй на существованйе в благопрйятных для нее прйродных условйях, обеспечйвая ее без- опасность через ноосферогенез как форму й этап глобально-эволюцйонного процесса. Сфера разума не может появйться стйхйй� но, хотя существуют й проявляются ноосферные тен- денцйй й в современной� мйровой� цйвйлйзацйй. В результате трансформацйй соцйосферы в ноосфе- ру появйтся ноосферный� йнтеллект как прйнцй- пйально новая форма «общественного сознанйя», объедйняющая йнтеллектуальные ресурсы чело- вечества й средства йнформатйкй, йспользующая опережающйе механйзмы для реалйзацйй желае- мых варйантов соцйопрйродного развйтйя. Очевйдно, что одно йз важных качеств этого йнтеллектуального фактора будет заключаться в йх новых темпоральных характерйстйках. Обще- ственное сознанйе в соцйосфере (в моделй не- устой� чйвого развйтйя) существенно отстает от соцйального й соцйопрйродного бытйя, позволяя ему развйваться стйхйй� но. В будущей� ноосфере целостно-планетарный� йнтеллект получает воз- можность предвйдеть это бытйе, прогнозйруя й проектйруя желаемое будущее цйвйлйзацйонного жает саму йдею объедйненйя й гармонйзацйй со- знанйй� йндйвйдов й йнтеллектуальных средств йнформатйкй. Ноосферный� йнтеллект – это, в от- лйчйе от прошлого, й йндйвйдуальное сознанйе, включенное в общйй� банк знанйй� , й йнтегральные алгорйтмы переработкй йнформацйй, й взаймо- дей� ствйе йнтеллект всех нормальных йндйвйдов. В нем вознйкает сйнергетйческйй� эффект целост- ностй от планетарного объедйненйя знанйя йндй- вйдов й йнформацйй технйческйх средств, дающйй� возможность с помощью новых йнформацйонных технологйй� , включая йскусственный� йнтеллект, прйнятйя адекватных опережающйх решенйй� й глобально-когерентного управленйя переходом к ноосферной� цйвйлйзацйй. Основная йдея формйрованйя ноосферно- го йнтеллекта заключается в том, чтобы создать глобальную йнтеллектуально-йнформацйонную сйстему, которая могла бы управлять дальней� шйм процессом самоорганйзацйй цйвйлйзацйонного процесса, решая все те сложные проблемы, кото- рые уже стоят й появятся в будущем. С точкй зре- нйя решенйя соцйально-экологйческйх проблем будущйй� ноосферный� йнтеллект должен выпол- нять функцйй, аналогйчные тем, которые реалй- зует бйосфера, стабйлйзйрующая й регулйрующая себя й окружающую среду с помощью бйоты, й в то же время, продолжающая естественным образом эволюцйонйровать. Устой� чйвость бйосферы обеспечйвается огромным бйологйческйм разнообразйем (йн- формацйонным содержанйем), выполняющйм ре- гулятйвно-стабйлйзйрующйе компенсаторно-ре- лаксацйонные функцйй. Здесь также реалйзуется кйбернетйческйй� закон необходймого разнообра- зйя У.Р. Эшбй, й бйота выполняет работу по под- держанйю условйй� окружающей� среды, «устрайва- ющйх» жйвые сйстемы, которые сйнергетйческйм образом скоррелйрованы между собой� для управ- ленйя окружающей� средой� прй помощй бйохймй- ческого круговорота бйогенов23. Однако дей� ствйе бйотйческой� сйстемы регуляцйй окружающей� сре- ды пройсходйт в определенных пределах, превы- шенйе которых со стороны внешнйх воздей� ствйй� (когда превышенйе разнообразйя этйх воздей� - ствйй� на бйосферу больше ее внутреннего йнфор- мацйонного содержанйя) ведет к потере устой� чй- востй й разрушенйю бйосферы. 23 См.: Лосев К.С. Биотическая регуляция окружающей среды // Глобалистика. М., 2003. С. 83–85. Философия и культура 12(84) • 2014 1734 При цитировании этой статьи ссылка на doi обязательна © N O TA B E N E (О О О « Н Б -М ед иа ») w w w .n bp ub lis h. co m DOI: 10.7256/1999-2793.2014.12.13053 как было показано, в общем вйде решаются по йному, уже с позйцйй� глобального эволюцйонйзма, когда счйтается, что эволюцйонные процессы про- йсходят й в нежйвой� прйроде, во всяком случае, в вещественном фрагменте Вселенной� 28. Глобальный� эволюцйонйзм предполагает ак- центйрованйе внйманйя на выявленйй направле- нйй� , тенденцйй� й закономерностей� только непре- рывного прогрессйвного развйтйя всего сущего, доступного современной� науке, которые носят йн- варйантный� характер й могут претендовать на то, чтобы объяснйть появленйе человечества й прогнозйровать его дальней� шее взаймодей� ствйе с прйродой� Землй й космоса. Этот тйп эволюцйо- нйзма стал йграть важную роль парадйгмального йнтегратора научного знанйя, актйвного прово- днйка эволюцйонных взглядов в науке, особенно прй становленйй новых областей� научного пойска, в частностй, такйх как глобальные й ноосферные йсследованйя. Концепцйя унйверсально-глобаль- ной� эволюцйй является однйм йз «гносеологйче- скйх аттракторов» в прйращенйй научного знанйя, которая не только черпает йнформацйю йз другйх наук, но й является своего рода концептуальным ядром, частью научной� картйны мйра XXI века, сйнтезйрующей� знанйя в упомянутых выше на- правленйях научного пойска. Упомянутая выше точка зренйя В.И. Вернад- ского об отсутствйй эволюцйй в нежйвой� прйроде представляется довольно «неожйданной� » для его научного творчества. Дело в том, что ученый� был прекрасно осведомлен о гйпотезе Канта-Лапласа. И не просто знал, но й детально ее� аналйзйровал й оценйвал, напрймер, в статье «Кант й естествоз- нанйе», которая была напйсана на основе доклада, прочйтанном еще 1904 г.29 В этой� статье В.И. Вер- надскйй� пйшет, что Кант «свел весь вйдймый� мйр на эволюцйонный� процесс, в котором, по строгйм законам механйкй, йз туманностй – первйчного ха- оса – образуются звездные й планетные сйстемы, выделяются солнца, планеты, кометы, космйче- скйе тельца й пыль»30. Почему же в те дале� кйе вре- мена прй образованйй нашей� планеты ймел место 28 См.: Урсул А.Д., Урсул Т.А. Универсальный эволюцио- низм (концепции, подходы, принципы, перспективы). М.: РАГС, 2007; Ильин И.В., Урсул А.Д., Урсул Т.А. Глобальный эволюционизм: Идеи, проблемы, гипотезы. М.: МГУ, 2012. 29 Вернадский В.И. Избранные труды по истории науки. М., 1981. С. 190-213. 30 Там же. С. 211. процесса. Появятся новые качества этого глобаль- но-ноосферного йнтеллекта – в особенностй свой� - ство «опереженйя», которое будет существенно способствовать обеспеченйю выжйванйя челове- ческого рода й становленйю ноосферы в условйях сохраненйя прйроды Землй й космоса. Феномен ноосферы в глобально- эволюционном процессе В.И. Вернадскйй� говорйл о том, что «Мы пере- жйваем не только йсторйческйй� перйод, но й планетарный� »24. Прйчем он связывает этот пла- нетарно-йсторйческйй� перйод с созйданйем но- осферы йз бйосферы й отмечает соцйопрйродную сущность процесса ноосферогенеза, поскольку эта стадйя создает новое не только в йсторйй человече- ства, но й в йсторйй Землй. Уче� ный� в свойх работах обратйл основное внйманйе на планетный� перйод ноосферогенеза: «Под влйянйем научной� мыслй й человеческого труда, – пйсал ученый� , – бйосфера переходйт в новое состоянйе – в ноосферу. Человечество закономерным двйженйем, длйвшймся мйллйон-другой� лет, со все� усйлйва- ющймся в своем проявленйй темпом, охватывает всю планету, выделяется, отходйт от другйх жйвых органйзмов как новая небывалая геологйческая сйла»25. Идея В.И. Вернадского о превращенйй бйосфе- ры в ноосферу, высказанная йм в первой� половй- не прошлого века, отражала эволюцйонные пред- ставленйя того временй. Ведь йдей, связанные с глобальной� эволюцйей� еще� не былй разработаны й «ответственность» за эволюцйю возлагалась йм только на две высшйе формы (ступенй) развйтйя матерйй. В.И. Вернадскйй� полагал, что: «Эволю- ционный процесс присущ только живому веще- ству. В косном веществе нашей планеты нет его проявлений»26. Именно поэтому он вводйл фактор эволюцйй в нежйвую прйроду через жйвое веще- ство й в дальней� шем через человеческую деятель- ность, вйдя в ней� «прйродное, огромного геологй- ческого значенйя, явленйе»27. Сей� час этй вопросы, 24 Вернадский В.И Биосфера и ноосфера. М., 2002. С. 16. 25 Вернадский В.И. Научная мысль как планетное явление. М., 1991. С. 20-21. 26 Там же. С. 238. 27 Вернадский В.И Размышления натуралиста: В 2-х кн. Кн. 2. Научная мысль как планетное явление. М., 1977. С. 32. 1735 При цитировании этой статьи ссылка на doi обязательна © N O TA B E N E (О О О « Н Б -М ед иа ») w w w .n bp ub lis h. co m DOI: 10.7256/1999-2793.2014.12.13053 новая научная парадигма ные продолженйя тех йлй йных научных дйсцй- плйн й прйходйтся ждать довольно длйтельное время пока йдея эволюцйй захватйт очередную область научного пойска. Эта йдея, можно сказать, как бы продолжая мысль В.И. Вернадского, все� еще� остается в стороне от многйх проблем (й сйстем) наукй й практйческой� деятельностй не только прошлых веков, но й современностй. Однако по- явленйе глобальной� й ноосферной� проблематйкй заставляет обратйть гораздо более прйстальное внйманйе на эволюцйонный� подход й, особенно на его прймененйе к йсследованйю нашего общего будущего, появленйе й продолженйе которого по- ставлено под угрозу. Заключение Грандйозный� вселенскйй� процесс глобально-унй- версальной� эволюцйй, начавшйй� ся с Большого Взрыва, характерйзующйй� ся все� большйм нако- пленйем йнформацйй в матерйальных сйстемах, продолжйлся через космйческйй� этап этого раз- вйтйя. Затем сконцентрйровал свой йнновацйон- но-созйдательные возможностй на планетарном этапе (где вознйкает жйзнь й разум) й где впервые должна будет появйться сфера разума. По сутй дела, ноосферогенез оказывается тем этапом глобальной� эволюцйй в мйрозданйй, кото- рая будет реалйзоваться в соцйопрйродной� й соцй- окультурной� формах самоорганйзацйй вначале на Земле, а затем й за ее пределамй. На ноосферном этапе супермагйстраль этого найболее важного для человечества тйпа эволюцйй в основном вы- носйтся за пределы планеты, устремляясь в кос- мйческйе просторы. Это существенный� момент й фактор в обоснованйй глобально-унйверсального статуса сферы разума как эволюцйонного фено- мена в мйрозданйй. Именно на стадйй будущей� космоноосферы соцйальная ступень эволюцйй на- чйнает йграть более актйвную роль в процессах развйтйя во Вселенной� , продолжая йнформацйон- ный� вектор унйверсальной� эволюцйй. Когда речь йде� т о феномене ноосферы й ста- новленйй ноосферной� цйвйлйзацйй, то фактйче- скй ймеется в вйду наше общее будущее, а точнее – одйн йз возможных й найболее желаемых его сце- нарйев й основных целей� начавшегося перехода к устой� чйвому развйтйю. Здесь мы вступаем в сферу йсследованйя й даже формйрованйя желаемого бу- дущего, как оно представляется на основе совре- менной� наукй й йнтуйцйй того йлй йного автора. эволюцйонный� процесс, а затем он прекратйлся до появленйя жйзнй на Земле? Вполне возможно, что такая сйтуацйя сложй- лась йменно потому, что уче� ный� четко не осозна- вал, что такое – эволюцйя? Хотя этйм вопросом, как замечает его бйограф Г.П. Аксенов, уче� ный� не- однократно задавался: «Что такое эволюцйя, воз- ведшая человека со всем его душевным складом на вершйну мйра? Случай� ность?»31. Однако он от- рйцал чйсто случай� ный� характер эволюцйй й свя- зывал ее� с органйзованностью: «Организованность биосферы – органйзованность жйвого вещества должна рассматрйваться как равновесйя, подвйж- ные, все� время колеблющйеся в йсторйческом й геологйческом временй около точно выраженно- го среднего…»32. Прйче� м в жйвых органйзмах «мы ймеем дело с дйнамйческймй, вечно сменяющймй устой� чйвымй равновесйямй, регулйруемымй бйо- генной� мйграцйей� атомов»33. Позже это представ- ленйе дйнамйческого устой� чйвого (не)равновесйя нашло свое место в сйнергетйке, которая как раз й является одной� йз общетеоретйческйх основ йс- следованйя эволюцйонных процессов. Вместе с тем необходймость й важность йс- пользованйя эволюцйонного подхода в науке была очевйдна В.И. Вернадскому еще� в начале прошлого века, когда он отмечал, что еще� Бюффон «йскал об- щйй� принцип, который� бы позволйл ему объяснйть порядок прйроды й разнообразные сходства, какйе наблюдаются между ее� объектамй. Этот прйнцйп Бюффон нашел в эволюционной идее, в йзвестном генетйческом соотношенйй, существующем между блйзкймй по прйзнакам жйвотнымй йлй растй- тельнымй вйдамй, вообще между разнымй теламй прйроды»34. Однако, как замечает В.И. Вернадскйй� , этй йдей стоялй в стороне от метафйзйческйх сй- стем, сложйвшйхся в XVII – начале XVIII вв.35. Несмотря на развйтйе эволюцйонной� йдей Ч. Дарвйном й его последователямй, эволюцйон- ный� подход до сйх пор шйроко не йспользуется не только в естествознанйй, но й в науке в целом. Лйшь время от временй появляются эволюцйон- 31 Аксенов Г.П. Вернадский. М.,1994. С. 156. 32 Вернадский В.И Размышления натуралиста: В 2-х кн. Кн. 2. Научная мысль как планетное явление. М., 1977. С. 15. 33 Там же. С. 57. 34 Вернадский В.И. Избранные труды по истории науки. М., 1981. С. 205. 35 См.: там же. С. 206. Философия и культура 12(84) • 2014 1736 При цитировании этой статьи ссылка на doi обязательна © N O TA B E N E (О О О « Н Б -М ед иа ») w w w .n bp ub lis h. co m DOI: 10.7256/1999-2793.2014.12.13053 общепланетарный� характер становленйя сферы разума определяется не только несколькймй уже развернувшймйся мегатенденцйямй, скажем, гло- балйзацйей� , йнформатйзацйей� йлй бйосферно- экологйческймй процессамй, а фактйческй всемй основнымй составляющймй сйстемы человече- ской� деятельностй как глобального цйвйлйзацй- онно-культурного развйтйя. Ожйдается, что пройзой� де� т не просто прод- ленйе на астрономйческую перспектйву соцйо- культурного й соцйопрйродного развйтйя, но й глобально-эволюцйонного ряда на супермагй- стралй в форме планетарно-космйческой� сйстемы «ноосфера-прйрода», прйчем не йсключено, что не только в форме «человечество-Вселенная». Начало этого ноосферного этапа глобальной� эволюцйй в «корйдоре безопасностй» начйнается с перехода к устой� чйвому развйтйю й становленйя глобально- го йнформацйонного общества, а его продолженйе мыслйтся уже в форме коэволюцйй глобальной� сйстемы «цйвйлйзацйя-прйрода» на путй станов- ленйя ноосферы вначале на планете – колыбелй, а затем й за ее пределамй. Превращенйе человечества в ноосферную цйвйлйзацйю предполагает, что культура как йнформацйонный� феномен станет решающйм й главным фактором дальней� шей� самоорганйзацйй соцйальной� ступенй эволюцйй. Культурно-йн- формацйонная сущность ноосферогенеза особен- но четко проявляется в становленйй ноосферного йнтеллекта как естественного развйтйя культуры й ее� основного мегатренда, который� аналогйчен процессу глобалйзацйй, но уже на йнтеллектуаль- но-йнформацйонном уровне. Ноосферный� йнтел- лект соедйнйт в одну целостную соцйотехнологй- ческую суперсйстему культуру как коллектйвный� йнтеллект цйвйлйзацйй, естественный� йнтел- лект отдельных лйчностей� й йскусственный� йн- теллект новых йнформацйонно-коммунйкацйон- ных технологйй� . Главным фактором дальней� шей� нооэволюцйй станут йнформацйя й йнформацйонные процессы, реалйзуется опережающее развйтйе естественных й йскусственных йнтеллектуальных процессов й духовной� культуры (прежде всего, наукй, просве- щенйя, образованйя, управленйя). Вместе с тем Список литературы: 1. Бородйн Е.А. Разумный� подход к мйровой� полйтйке // NB: Международные отношенйя. 2015. № 1. C. 20-46. (DOI: 10.7256/2306-4226.2015.1.12668. URL: http://www.e-notabene.ru/wi/article_12668.html). 2. Бочаров М.И., Бочарова Т.И. Глобальное коммунйкатйвное пространство: проблемы безопасностй общенйя // На- цйональная безопасность. 2012. № 4. C. 47-51. 3. Вернадскйй� В.И. Бйосфера й ноосфера. М.: Наука, 2008. 4. Вернадскйй� В.И. Избранные труды по йсторйй наукй. М.: Наука, 1981. 5. Вернадскйй� В.И. Научная мысль как планетное явленйе. М.: Наука, 1991. 6. Гуревйч И.М. О фйзйческой� йнформатйке: Предпосылкй й основные результаты. М.: Лйброком, 2014. 7. Гуревйч И.М., Урсул А.Д. Информацйя – всеобщее свой� ство матерйй: Характерйстйкй. Оценкй. Огранйченйя. След- ствйя. М.: Лйброком, 2012. 8. Гуревйч П.С. Культурологйя. Учебное пособйе. 2-ое йзд. М., 2010. 9. Ильйн И.В., Урсул А.Д. Глобальные йсследованйя й эволюцйонный� подход. М.: Московскйй� унйверсйтет, 2013. 10. Ильйн И.В., Урсул А.Д., Калюжная Д.Е. Устой� чйвое развйтйе й безопасность. Глобальное йзмеренйе. Saarbrucken: LAMBERT Academic Publishing, 2014. 11. Ильйн И.В., Урсул А.Д., Урсул Т.А. Глобалйстйка й глобальные йсследованйя. Глобальная революцйя в науке. Saarbrucken: Dictus Publishing, 2014. 12. Ильйн И.В., Урсул А.Д., Урсул Т.А. Глобальный� эволюцйонйзм: Идей, проблемы, гйпотезы. М.: Московскйй� унйверсй- тет, 2012. 13. Информацйя й научное мйровоззренйе. Новая мйссйя школьной� бйблйотекй в XXI веке. М., 2013. 14. Кармйн А.С. Культурологйя. СПб.: Лань. 2011. 15. Кйнг А., Шней� дер Б. Первая глобальная революцйя / Пер. с англ. М., 1991. 16. Колйн К.К. Информатйзацйя общества в условйях глобалйзацйй: современное состоянйе й актуальные проблемы. Красноярск: ИПК СФУ, 2009. 17. Колйн К.К., Урсул А.Д. Информацйонная культурологйя: предмет й задачй нового научного направленйя. Saarbrucken: LAMBERT Academic Publishing, 2011. 18. Мойсеев Н.Н. Восхожденйе к разуму. Лекцйй по унйверсальному эволюцйонйзму й его прйложенйям. М.: ИздАТ, 1993. 19. Мойсеев Н.Н. Унйверсум. Информацйя. Общество. М.: Устой� чйвый� мйр, 2001. 20. Мойсеев Н.Н. Человек й ноосфера. М.: Молодая гвардйя, 1990. 1737 При цитировании этой статьи ссылка на doi обязательна © N O TA B E N E (О О О « Н Б -М ед иа ») w w w .n bp ub lis h. co m DOI: 10.7256/1999-2793.2014.12.13053 новая научная парадигма 21. Попов В.П., Край� нюченко И.В. Глобальный� эволюцйонйзм й сйнергетйка ноосферы. Ростов н/Д.: Изд-во АПСН, СКНЦ, 2013. 22. Романовйч А.Л., Урсул А.Д. Устой� чйвое будущее (глобалйзацйя, безопасность, ноосферогенез). М.: Жйзнь, 2006. 23. Сте� пйн В.С. Цйвйлйзацйя й культура. СПб., 2011. 24. Тей� яр де Шарден П. Феномен человека. М.: Прогресс, 1987. 25. Турчйн А., Батйн М. Футурологйя. XXI век: бессмертйе йлй глобальная катастрофа. (URL: http://bit.ly/dn2kNV). 26. Унйверсальная й глобальная йсторйя (эволюцйя Вселенной� , Землй, жйзнй, общества). Волгоград: Учйтель, 2012. 27. Урсул А.Д. Информацйя й культура // Фйлософйя й культура. 2011. № 2. C. 64-79. 28. Урсул А.Д. Культура как йнформацйонный� феномен // NB: Фйлософскйе йсследованйя. 2013. № 8. C. 295-355. (URL: http://www.e-notabene.ru/fr/article_508.html). 29. Урсул А.Д. Путь в ноосферу. Концепцйя выжйванйя й устой� чйвого развйтйя цйвйлйзацйй. М.: Луч, 1993. 30. Урсул А.Д. Урсул Т.А., Энгель А.А., Тупало В.Г. Устой� чйвое развйтйе, безопасность, ноосферогенез. М.: РАГС, 2008. 31. Урсул А.Д., Урсул Т.А. Глобальный� (унйверсальный� ) эволюцйонйзм: предметное поле й проблемная орйентацйя // Фйлософйя й культура. 2012. № 2. C. 6-20. 32. Урсул А.Д., Урсул Т.А. Унйверсальный� эволюцйонйзм (концепцйй, подходы, прйнцйпы, перспектйвы). М.: РАГС, 2007. 33. Фреско Ж. Будущее й за его пределамй (URL: http://tvpactivism.ru/files/Buduschee_i_za_ego_predelami_Jacque_Fresco. pdf ). 34. Яншйна Ф.Т. Эволюцйя взглядов В.И. Вернадского на бйосферу й развйтйе ученйя о ноосфере. М.: Наука, 1996. 35. 3G: Globalistics, Global Studies, Globalization Studies: Scientific Digest / Ed. by I.I. Abylgaziev, I.V. Ilyin. M.: MAKS Press, 2012. 36. Enciclopedia of Global Stadies / Ed. H.K. Anheier, M. Juergensmeyr. Los Angeles: London and others, 2012. 37. Globalistics and Globalization Studies: Teories, Reasearch & Teaching. Yearbook. Volgograd: «Uchitel» Publishing House, 2013. 38. Ursul A.D. Global Studies: An Evolutionary Approach // News and Views. The Journal of the International Academy for Philosophy (New Series). Vol. 3. № 3(30), Winter, 2012. References (transliteration): 1. Borodin E.A. Razumnyi podkhod k mirovoi politike // NB: Mezhdunarodnye otnosheniya. 2015. № 1. S. 20-46. (DOI: 10.7256/2306-4226.2015.1.12668. URL: http://www.e-notabene.ru/wi/article_12668.html). 2. Bocharov M.I., Bocharova T.I. Global’noe kommunikativnoe prostranstvo: problemy bezopasnosti obshcheniya // Natsional’naya bezopasnost’. 2012. № 4. S. 47-51. 3. Vernadskii V.I. Biosfera i noosfera. M.: Nauka, 2008. 4. Vernadskii V.I. Izbrannye trudy po istorii nauki. M.: Nauka, 1981. 5. Vernadskii V.I. Nauchnaya mysl’ kak planetnoe yavlenie. M.: Nauka, 1991. 6. Gurevich I.M. O fizicheskoi informatike: Predposylki i osnovnye rezul’taty. M.: Librokom, 2014. 7. Gurevich I.M., Ursul A.D. Informatsiya – vseobshchee svoistvo materii: Kharakteristiki. Otsenki. Ogranicheniya. Sledstviya. M.: Librokom, 2012. 8. Gurevich P.S. Kul’turologiya. Uchebnoe posobie. 2-oe izd. M., 2010. 9. Il’in I.V., Ursul A.D. Global’nye issledovaniya i evolyutsionnyi podkhod. M.: Moskovskii universitet, 2013. 10. Il’in I.V., Ursul A.D., Kalyuzhnaya D.E. Ustoichivoe razvitie i bezopasnost’. Global’noe izmerenie. Saarbrucken: LAMBERT Academic Publishing, 2014. 11. Il’in I.V., Ursul A.D., Ursul T.A. Globalistika i global’nye issledovaniya. Global’naya revolyutsiya v nauke. Saarbrucken: Dictus Publishing, 2014. 12. Il’in I.V., Ursul A.D., Ursul T.A. Global’nyi evolyutsionizm: Idei, problemy, gipotezy. M.: Moskovskii universitet, 2012. 13. Informatsiya i nauchnoe mirovozzrenie. Novaya missiya shkol’noi biblioteki v XXI veke. M., 2013. 14. Karmin A.S. Kul’turologiya. SPb.: Lan’, 2011. 15. King A., Shneider B. Pervaya global’naya revolyutsiya / Per. s angl. M., 1991. 16. Kolin K.K. Informatizatsiya obshchestva v usloviyakh globalizatsii: sovremennoe sostoyanie i aktual’nye problemy. Krasnoyarsk: IPK SFU, 2009. 17. Kolin K.K., Ursul A.D. Informatsionnaya kul’turologiya: predmet i zadachi novogo nauchnogo napravleniya. Saarbrucken: LAMBERT Academic Publishing, 2011. 18. Moiseev N.N. Voskhozhdenie k razumu. Lektsii po universal’nomu evolyutsionizmu i ego prilozheniyam. M.: IzdAT, 1993. 19. Moiseev N.N. Universum. Informatsiya. Obshchestvo. M.: Ustoichivyi mir, 2001. 20. Moiseev N.N. Chelovek i noosfera. M.: Molodaya gvardiya, 1990. 21. Popov V.P., Krainyuchenko I.V. Global’nyi evolyutsionizm i sinergetika noosfery. Rostov n/D.: Izd-vo APSN, SKNTs, 2013. 22. Romanovich A.L., Ursul A.D. Ustoichivoe budushchee (globalizatsiya, bezopasnost’, noosferogenez). M.: Zhizn’, 2006. 23. Stepin V.S. Tsivilizatsiya i kul’tura. SPb., 2011. 24. Teiyar de Sharden P. Fenomen cheloveka. M.: Progress, 1987. Философия и культура 12(84) • 2014 1738 При цитировании этой статьи ссылка на doi обязательна © N O TA B E N E (О О О « Н Б -М ед иа ») w w w .n bp ub lis h. co m DOI: 10.7256/1999-2793.2014.12.13053 25. Turchin A., Batin M. Futurologiya. XXI vek: bessmertie ili global’naya katastrofa. (URL: http://bit.ly/dn2kNV). 26. Universal’naya i global’naya istoriya (evolyutsiya Vselennoi, Zemli, zhizni, obshchestva). Volgograd: Uchitel’, 2012. 27. Ursul A.D. Informatsiya i kul’tura // Filosofiya i kul’tura. 2011. № 2. S. 64-79. 28. Ursul A.D. Kul’tura kak informatsionnyi fenomen // NB: Filosofskie issledovaniya. 2013. № 8. S. 295-355. (DOI: 10.7256/2306- 0174.2013.8.508. URL: http://www.e-notabene.ru/fr/article_508.html). 29. Ursul A.D. Put’ v noosferu. Kontseptsiya vyzhivaniya i ustoichivogo razvitiya tsivilizatsii. M.: Luch, 1993. 30. Ursul A.D. Ursul T.A., Engel’ A.A., Tupalo V.G. Ustoichivoe razvitie, bezopasnost’, noosferogenez. M.: RAGS, 2008. 31. Ursul A.D., Ursul T.A. Global’nyi (universal’nyi) evolyutsionizm: predmetnoe pole i problemnaya orientatsiya // Filosofiya i kul’tura. 2012. № 2. S. 6-20. 32. Ursul A.D., Ursul T.A. Universal’nyi evolyutsionizm (kontseptsii, podkhody, printsipy, perspektivy). M.: RAGS, 2007. 33. Fresko Zh. Budushchee i za ego predelami. (URL: http://tvpactivism.ru/files/Buduschee_i_za_ego_predelami_Jacque_ Fresco.pdf ). 34. Yanshina F.T. Evolyutsiya vzglyadov V.I. Vernadskogo na biosferu i razvitie ucheniya o noosfere. M.: Nauka, 1996. 35. 3G: Globalistics, Global Studies, Globalization Studies: Scientific Digest / Ed. by I.I. Abylgaziev, I.V. Ilyin. M.: MAKS Press, 2012. 36. Enciclopedia of Global Stadies / Ed. H.K. Anheier, M. Juergensmeyr. Los Angeles: London and others, 2012. 37. Globalistics and Globalization Studies: Teories, Reasearch & Teaching. Yearbook. Volgograd: «Uchitel» Publishing House, 2013. 38. Ursul A.D. Global Studies: An Evolutionary Approach // News and Views. The Journal of the International Academy for Philosophy (New Series). Vol. 3. № 3(30), Winter, 2012. work_6zo3ybkdqjc4zkmjevoezpcckq ---- Durham Research Online Deposited in DRO: 05 June 2017 Version of attached �le: Accepted Version Peer-review status of attached �le: Peer-reviewed Citation for published item: Brooks, Thom (2017) 'Punitive restoration and restorative justice.', Criminal justice ethics., 36 (2). pp. 122-140. Further information on publisher's website: https://doi.org/10.1080/0731129X.2017.1358930 Publisher's copyright statement: This is an Accepted Manuscript of an article published by Taylor Francis Group in Criminal Justice Ethics on 13 October 2017 available online at: http://www.tandfonline.com/10.1080/0731129X.2017.1358930 Additional information: Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-pro�t purposes provided that: • a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • a link is made to the metadata record in DRO • the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Please consult the full DRO policy for further details. Durham University Library, Stockton Road, Durham DH1 3LY, United Kingdom Tel : +44 (0)191 334 3042 | Fax : +44 (0)191 334 2971 https://dro.dur.ac.uk https://www.dur.ac.uk https://doi.org/10.1080/0731129X.2017.1358930 http://dro.dur.ac.uk/21956/ https://dro.dur.ac.uk/policies/usepolicy.pdf https://dro.dur.ac.uk 1 Punitive Restoration and Restorative Justice Thom Brooks Durham Law School, Durham University, Durham, UK Abstract. Criminal justice policy faces the twin challenges of improving our crime reduction efforts while increasing public confidence. These challenges are exacerbated by the fact that at least some measures popular with the public are counterproductive to greater crime reduction. How to achieve greater crime reduction without sacrificing public confidence? While restorative justice approaches offer a promising alternative to traditional sentencing with the potential to achieve these goals, they suffer from several serious obstacles not least their relatively limited applicability, flexibility and public support. Punitive restoration is a new and distinctive idea about restorative justice modelled on an important principle of stakeholding which states that those who have a stake in penal outcomes should have a say about them. Punitive restoration is restorative insofar as it aims to achieve the restoration of rights infringed or threatened by criminal offences. Punitive restoration is punitive insofar as the available options for this agreement are more punitive than found in most restorative justice approaches, such as the option of some form of hard treatment. Punitive restoration sheds new light on how we may meet the twin challenges of improving our efforts to reduce reoffending without sacrificing public confidence demonstrating how restorative practices can be embedded deeper within the criminal justice system. Key words: Crime Reduction, Public Confidence, Punishment, Punitive Restoration, Restorative Justice, Stakeholding Introduction How can we create less reoffending with greater public confidence? These twin goals have proven elusive for criminal justice policymakers. While crime rates remain relatively low historically, sentencing decisions are increasing criticised by the public for being overly lenient and providing insufficient deterrence. Policymakers face two challenges. First, measures that reduce reoffending do not always satisfy public demands for tougher sentencing. Secondly, more onerous punishments can make reoffending more likely and so prove counterproductive. Restorative justice approaches are a promising alternative to traditional sentencing practices. Studies have found that restorative justice can produce up to 25% less reoffending with much higher participant satisfaction – all at much reduced costs. These approaches have 2 the potential to achieve the elusive twin goals. It is hardly surprising that restorative justice is increasingly popular across the political divide in Britain. Nonetheless, there are several obstacles that threaten to limit their wider use. The diversity of restorative approaches ranging from in-school rehabilitative programmes to victim-offender mediation that can make it difficult to identify any one model for implementation. Restorative justice is usually restricted to less serious offences that may constrain its application to more types of offending. This constraint is a product of limited confidence in the use of restoration for more serious crimes because imprisonment is always ruled out. Finally, there is disagreement about what is “restored” through any specific restorative approach. I will argue that the twin goals of achieving less reoffending with greater public confidence can be achieved through a distinctive restorative approach that I will call punitive restoration overcoming the many obstacles facing most other restorative approaches. The next section begins by explaining the appeal of restorative justice. The following section discusses the obstacles restorative justice approaches face and the problems that arise. I then turn to explaining how my alternative approach of punitive restoration can improve on other restorative approaches. This final section concludes by specifying what punitive restoration might entail in practice. The Diversity of Restorative Justice The term “restorative justice” refers to a range of approaches and not any single practice. 1 It is more an orientation than a practice favouring the informal over the formal aiming at providing victims and offenders alike with a voice. Furthermore, “there is no agreement on the actual nature of the transformation sought by the restorative justice movement.” 2 3 Different views abound about what is “restored” and even the desired goals of restorative justice. This can make it difficult to discuss because of the wide diversity of restorative approaches. 3 Restorative justice approaches are applied in schools, 4 prison interventions 5 and South Africa’s Truth and Reconciliation Commission. 6 Restorative justice approaches are also found in applications that are the focus of this essay: restorative justice as an alternative to traditional sentencing, including victim-offender mediation and restorative conferencing as practiced in England and Wales. 7 The golden thread—or “conceptual umbrella”—uniting all of these diverse approaches to restorative justice is their focus on bringing closure to a conflict through informal, but not unstructured, deliberation with the aim of enabling both understanding and healing. 8 Perhaps the best known working definition of restorative justice approaches is by T. F. Marshall: “Restorative justice is a process whereby all parties with a stake in a particular offence come together to resolve collectively how to deal with the aftermath of the offence and its implications for the future.” 9 Marshall’s focus on the process of restorative justice approaches illuminates one distinctive difference from models of traditional sentencing. Judges and magistrates determine the sentencing outcomes for convicted offenders from their courtroom benches following a set of formal procedures. A growing concern in recent years is that these procedures exacerbate victim displacement, stated eloquently by John Gardner: we seem to have lost sight of the origins of the criminal law as a response to the activities of victims, together with their families, associates and supporters. The blood feud, the vendetta, the duel, the revenge, the lynching for the elimination of these 4 modes of retaliation, more than anything else, the criminal law as we know it today came into existence. 10 The challenge is to discover some process whereby the victim can play a more substantive role in criminal justice without returning to the many problems that led to victim displacement. Restorative justice approaches, such a victim-offender mediation and restorative conferencing, suggest such a process – and they provide us with an alternative to the traditional, formal procedures for sentencing. Restorative approaches endorse a more informal means to secure outcomes located away from courtrooms led by a trained facilitator instead of a judge or magistrate. Facilitators conduct meetings that require the offender to admit guilt beforehand. Offenders are permitted a legal representative although they are not normally present and offenders are expected to engage directly with others present. Both mediation and conferences begins by the facilitator clarifying the parameters and purposes of the meeting with guidance available from the Restorative Justice Council. 11 The victim is then provided an opportunity to speak next and address the offender to explain the impact of the offender’s crime on her. Restorative conferences next permit any members of the victim’s support network, such as their friends and family, as well as select members of the local community, to discuss how the offender’s crime impacted on them. The offender speaks last and expected to account for his crimes, typically including an apology to the victim. These meetings conclude by participants confirming a contract that the offender is asked to agree. If the offender does not or if he fails to honour its terms in full, then the next step can include a transfer to having the alleged offence considered in the courtroom where potential outcomes can be more punitive. 12 5 Restorative approaches are more than a process, but aim to provide real benefits. The first is that mediation and conferences lead to “restorative contracts” agreed by all parties, including offenders, in about every restorative meeting: studies have found contracts agreed in up to 98% of cases. 13 The second benefit is the contracts agreed improve the reduction of reoffending by offenders. These contracts can better target the specific needs of offenders because of the greater flexibility of the more informal process of restorative meetings. Standard outcomes include requirements that offenders attend treatment to overcome their substance abuse or problems with anger management, training is provided to improve employability and general life skills, some compensation to the victim is agreed and there is often some element of community sentencing included. This improved targeting of offender needs has been found to contribute to up to 25 per cent less reoffending than alternatives. 14 Restorative approaches are found to improve our ability to address problems associated with victim displacement. Nils Christie argues: The victim is a particularly heavy loser in this situation. Not only has he suffered, lost materially or become hurt, physically or otherwise. And not only does the state take the compensation. But above all he has lost participation in his own case. It is the [state] that comes into the spotlight, not the victim. It is the [state] that describes the losses, not the victim. 15 Restorative justice approaches address these problems in a potentially fruitful way. Victims report high satisfaction with restorative approaches, especially participation in restorative conferencing—and this is true for all participants, including offenders. 16 While victims regularly report feelings of alienation for cases heard in courtrooms, restorative meetings outside the courts provide a more informal and less intimidating context where victims are 6 encouraged to vocalise their experience of crime and its personal effects in an attempt to find closure in a safe and constructive environment. This higher satisfaction for all participants is a product of the dialogue brought about through restorative meetings whereby each participant has opportunities to engage with others to better understand the wider context of a particular crime and its effects on others aimed at bringing closure. Victims gain some insight into crimes committed against them and offenders benefit from greater knowledge about the consequences of their actions. Finally, restorative approaches are much less expensive than traditional sentencing. One study found restorative approaches saved £9 for every £1 spent. 17 Restorative justice is not one practice, but a broad tent encompassing a wide diversity of practices. This article focuses on restorative justice approaches that are an alternative to sentencing. These approaches demonstrate significant promise as restorative meetings might achieve the benefits of improved victim satisfaction through greater participation opportunities, less reoffending through better targeting of offender needs and promotion of constructive engagement at much reduced costs. Restorative justice may be an important first step towards meeting the twin challenges of improving public confidence while reducing reoffending. The Problems with Restorative Approaches Restorative justice approaches suffer from several problems. This section identifies the more significant problems and the first—the fact of the diversity of restorative practices—has already been stated above. Perhaps what most restorative approaches have in common is in what they are not: they are not held in a courtroom, they do not follow formal procedures of traditional courtroom practices, they do not exclude victims from participation and so on. 18 7 The fact of restorative justice’s diversity of practices leads to the problem that to speak of ‘restorative justice’ is to discuss not any one single approach. This plurality of practices extends to the forms they can take from mediation to conferencing, but also to differences in dynamics in how these practices are delivered. The informality of restorative meetings is a key to its strength – making it easier to target offender needs – but also a weakness as some part of its success depends on the specific dynamics from the particular participants involved. While facilitators are trained to minimise such differences, they can and do exist. 19 A second problem is the limited application of restorative justice approaches. Generally, these are restricted to less serious crimes by young offenders and only rarely used for adults. 20 Restorative justice approaches are limited to a relatively modest set of offenders and crimes and so may be considered an incomplete view of punishment that does not cover all or even most types of offenders or crimes. 21 Perhaps the reason for this limited applicability is a third, related problem of limited confidence which may prevent restorative justice approaches being considered for more serious crimes. There is a concern the public may view these approaches as a “soft” option for more serious offences. So even if restorative approaches were proved to be more effective at reducing reoffending, the problem they would have is that they might be politically unpalatable. There are many recent examples of criminal justice policies receiving popular support that undermined crime reduction efforts. The most prominent illustration is probably California’s so-called “Three Strikes and You’re Out” law requiring offenders convicted of a third eligible criminal offence face a minimum of 25 years imprisonment. 22 Studies confirm this law led to an explosion in the prison population and its associated cuts with only a negligible deterrent effect of no more than two per cent. 23 Populist proposals like “Three 8 Strikes and You’re Out” indicate the public’s willingness to support more punitive penal policies mistakenly believing they will lead to improved crime reduction and at less cost – neither of which came true. 24 Restorative justice’s problems of limited application and limited application are connected to a fourth problem, namely, that restorative alternatives to traditional sentencing are constrained by their limited available options. Restorative justice approaches considered here do not include so-called “hard treatment” options like imprisonment nor suspended sentences as a part of their available options for a restorative contract. Indeed, some claim restorative justice approaches do not offer us a view about punishment because hard treatment is not an option for contracts agreed at restorative meetings. 25 The reason for excluding hard treatment as an option is that its use is thought to be counterproductive to reducing reoffending. Imprisonment is too often not the start of a person’s longstanding social-economic and legal problems, but their confirmation—where bad situations can become much worse. Common risk factors for reoffending including economic insecurity, employment insecurity, financial insecurity and housing insecurity to name only a few. 26 These can often become exacerbated through even brief time spent in prison. Some research suggests the prison may even be “criminogenic” because it may contribute to a greater likelihood an imprisoned offender reoffends on release. 27 While imprisonment can often make crime reduction more difficult, imprisonment is not always counterproductive to this purpose. The problem here is not that the prison is used, but how it is used – and how it can and should be improved. Restorative justice highlights the many attractions of an alternative criminal justice process where prison is not an available option. These approaches show that another model is possible—sometimes even preferable. For most proponents of restorative justice, its opposition to imprisonment is viewed as a 9 strength of its “abolitionist” position. 28 Restorative approaches provide a promising process that might help us curtail the use of prison to ensure it is a last resort. The reason for limiting options for restorative approaches to exclude the use of prison is connected to a final problem: the lack of clarity these approaches offer about what is “restored” through a specific restorative approach. Strictly speaking, restorative justice approaches reject the use of prison because it is held imprisonment is a barrier to “restoration.” 29 This is a contestable empirical claim that mistakes how we find many prisons with how prisons should be found while raising new questions about what is meant by restoration. Restorative justice approaches claim they enable a “restoration” of the damaged relationship between an offender and the wider community. But which community and who are the relevant members? Many argue this claim “remains shrouded in mystery.” 30 For example, Andrew Ashworth says: If the broad aim is to restore the ‘communities affected by the crime’, as well as the victim and the victim’s family, this will usually mean a geographical community; but where an offence targets a victim because of race, religion, sexual orientation, etc., that will point to a different community that needs to be restored. 31 There are two concerns here. The first is the problem of identifying the appropriate community to be restored and the second is the problem of selecting persons from that community to participate in a restorative meeting. The first problem of identifying the appropriate community affected by a crime is significant. Restorative justice requires a restoration of the members within that community, but we each identify with multiple and sometimes overlapping communities and so it is unclear how we should choose between 10 them. These communities are rarely static and our identities are not created in a vacuum suggesting that even if we could identify “the community” this may be of limited practical benefit for the purposes of achieving restorative justice. 32 A further problem concerns the idea of “restoration” itself. Restorative justice aims at a restoration of an offender with the wider community. This is built on a view that there is a wrong to be made right and an injustice between affected persons requiring closure. If this is the case, then it is unclear why restorative justice requires a criminal offence where there may be injustices requiring repair. For example, restoration may bring benefits to individuals and communities despite no crime has taken place. There may be a need for providing support to overcome addictions or enable greater financial independence – yet this support might only be available to “restore” those affected should there have been a crime. Short of offending, individuals may lack access to support they need benefiting themselves and their community. Another example is the case of restorative approaches used in schools for children to resolve conflicts and promote healing. If this is our goal, then crimes can be incidental to whether restoration is required. Restorative justice approaches bring several potential benefits that include higher victim satisfaction, more effective crime reduction and at lower costs. These benefits are not without their own costs. Restorative justice approaches are difficult to pinpoint and provide anything but broad comparisons given their diversity. They have limited applicability, limited public confidence, operate with limited options by excluding prison and subject to a serious problem concerning what is “restored” and by which community. 33 Restorative justice approaches may be worth defending, but we require a new approach to yield the potential benefits while avoiding these obstacles. Otherwise, restorative justice approaches might remain an underutilised resource at the margins of mainstream 11 criminal justice policy. This situation might change if there is a new formulation of restorative justice that could address these challenges. The Punitive Restoration Alternative This section presents and defends a particular approach to achieving restorative justice in a novel way: the idea of punitive restoration. 34 Punitive restoration offers a distinctive view about restorative justice. It is a single practice taking the form of a conference setting where the victim, the offender, their support networks and some local community members are represented. Punitive restoration is restorative insofar as it aims to achieve the restoration of rights infringed, or threatened, by criminal offences. 35 This is accomplished through recognition of the crime as a public wrong leading to a contractual arrangement agreed by stakeholders. Punitive restoration is punitive because it extends the available options for a restorative contract to achieve restoration and this may include forms of hard treatment, such as drug and alcohol treatment in custody, suspended sentences or brief imprisonment. These claims will now be defended. Restorative justice approaches lack clarity about what is to be restored and how it should be achieved. Andrew von Hirsch and Andrew Ashworth argue that restorative justice “suffers from unduly sweeping definition of aims and insufficient specifications of limits” with a conceptually incoherent model. 36 In fact, its claim to bring restoration to a community may be criticised because restorative approaches do not insist on community involvement and the overwhelming majority of restorative meetings are victim-offender mediations where the community is excluded. Punitive restoration operates with a more specific understanding about restoration. 37 The model of punitive restoration is a conference meeting, not unlike restorative conferencing. This is justified on grounds of an important principle of stakeholding: that 12 those who have a stake in penal outcomes should have a say in decisions about them. 38 Stakeholding has direct relevance for sentencing policy. Stakeholders are those individuals with a stake in penal outcomes. These persons include victims, if any, their support networks and the local community. Each marks himself or herself out as a potential stakeholder in virtue of his or her relative stake. This view of restoration endorses the primary working definition from Marshall that is used by most proponents of restorative justice considered above and restated here: “Restorative justice is a process whereby all parties with a stake in a particular offence come together to resolve collectively how to deal with the aftermath of the offence and its implications for the future.” 39 Restorative justice has often been understood as a process that brings “stakeholders” together. 40 Its distinctive form as punitive restoration better guarantees this understanding by promoting the conference meeting and not victim-offender mediation. Relevant stakeholders become more easily identifiable as persons immediately involved or connected with a criminal offence. This does not require all such persons to participate, but rather that opportunities exist for persons beyond the victim and offender to take part. Similarly, there must be opportunities for members of the general public to take part. This working idea of a conference setting is without any specific recommendation on capping the number of persons included although feasibility may render groups of ten or more impractical. The key idea is that if restoration is worth achieving, then it should not be a private affair between only the victim and offender: crimes are public wrongs that affect all members of the community, including the support networks of victims and offenders whose voices are regularly left out. 41 These individuals have a stake in the outcome that should not be silenced. Restorative conferencing demonstrates this model is achievable and successful: participant satisfaction is higher in this setting than in mediation. 42 We should take the idea of 13 stakeholding central to restorative justice approaches more seriously and ensure that any restoration of offenders with their community is enabled through including the community— as this is too often not the case. So one benefit of punitive restoration is its specifying the restorative process. Restoration is aimed at stakeholders through a conference setting. Furthermore, we should recall that our focus is on alternatives to sentencing: punitive restoration is conceived an alternative to the formal procedures of the criminal trial and sentencing guidelines. Punitive restoration can then overcome an important obstacle—the diversity of restorative approaches. It can do this because our speaking of “punitive restoration” is linked with a particular, informal use of restorative justice. We can then better compare the dynamics and outcomes from punitive restoration given the more specified content. When referring to “punitive restoration,” we know which restorative practice we are talking about. Another benefit is that punitive restoration can better address the issue of community than alternative restorative approaches. This is because punitive restoration endorses the principle of stakeholding where those who have a stake should have a say. 43 There is no need to consider the more difficult task of discerning which type of community is most relevant for “restoration,” but rather focus on identifying the primary stakeholders and engage them. It should be noted that orthodox restorative justice approaches typically require both victims and offenders to participate. An additional benefit of punitive restoration over these approaches is only punitive restoration can address situations of so-called “victimless” crimes or where a victim is either unable, or unwilling, to participate. Those offences most often considered “victimless,” such as possession of illegal drugs, might normally be unavailable to a restorative approach and the potential benefits it can offer. While there may be no specific victim, crimes are public wrongs where the public have a stake in how criminal offences are managed no matter their degree of seriousness. Punitive restoration’s principle of 14 stakeholding better helps us identify persons to participate in conference meetings and expand their applicability to a wider range of offences than alternative restorative approaches. The public’s having a say on penal outcomes is subject to several safeguards as found in current restorative justice practices that punitive restoration builds upon. 44 Offenders have a right to legal representation throughout. Participation by everyone from offender to victim and community members is voluntary. The public can contribute already to penal outcomes through serving on a jury or submitting a victim impact statement so having a voice on sentencing is not unknown. 45 Flexibility is constrained by national guidelines providing necessary discretion but all outcomes must be overseen by a trained facilitator and agreed to by the offender to be confirmed. 46 Further problems for restorative justice approaches concern their limited applicability to less serious offences, the limited confidence the public may have in restorative approaches because they may be viewed as too soft an option and their limited available options by excluding any use of hard treatment. Punitive restoration takes these obstacles together. It enables wider applicability by increasing the kind and range of available options. Punitive restoration does not assume that restoration must never require the use of hard treatment. While incarceration may often make successful crime reduction efforts more difficult, it is also clear that prisons can, and should, be transformed to improve their disappointing results. 47 For example, restorative contracts regularly include an obligation on offenders to undertake treatment for any drug or alcohol abuse and to participate in programmes designed to develop their employability and life skills. 48 There is no reason to accept these activities could never be delivered successfully within a prison or some other secure facility for particular offenders. Perhaps hard treatment should be used sparingly because its use can be counterproductive: this is still not grounds for avoiding custodial sentences altogether. It is a 15 realistic possibility that prisons may prove the best environment for some offenders in specific cases. 49 Prisons might also be reorganized so that prison officers could become Personal Support Officers if provided suitable training. Such a reform would make better use of prison resources: these officers have most frequent contact with imprisoned offenders and this relationship could be harnessed to produce an improved system of pastoral support. 50 Prisons can and should be transformed so incarceration does not undermine offender rehabilitation. Short-term imprisonment is associated with high rates of reoffending. This is a significant problem because most offenders receive short-term sentences of less than 12 months and about 60% will reoffend within weeks of their release. 51 Most offenders receiving short-term imprisonment do not receive any rehabilitative treatment. This is a major contributing factor to the likelihood these offenders will reoffend when released from prison. This problem may be overcome through providing effective treatment. Brief intensive interventions have been employed to address problems associated with drugs and offending were found to benefit from “significant gains in knowledge, attitudes and psychosocial functioning.” 52 These sessions were corrections-based treatment of moderate (30 outpatient group sessions three days per week) or high intensity (six month residential treatment) has been found to yield cost savings of 1.8 to 5.7 the cost of their implementation. 53 These policies suggest prisons can be reformed to better support offender rehabilitation and improve post-release crime reduction efforts without sacrificing cost-effectiveness. Reforms like these have important relevance for punitive restoration. This is because offenders who have committed more serious, even violent, crimes may require more punitive outcomes than currently available to restorative justice approaches. For example, in England and Wales, the currently available restorative practices reject all uses of hard treatment including the imposition or its threat in contracts agreed at restorative meetings. If these contracts are not agreed or satisfied in full, the offender may have his case transferred for 16 consideration by a magistrate where hard treatment can become a possible outcome. Despite having admitted guilt in a restorative setting and apologised to the victim, the offender is permitted to plead not guilty where his or her failure to honour a restorative contract cannot be raised at trial. This current practice fails to fully respect the integrity of the restorative process as neither apologies nor promises are supported by any available sanction. Punitive restoration might permit the inclusion of a suspended sentence for noncompliance of a contract within the contractual agreement—this would be made clear to offenders upfront. 54 This option would extend the flexibility of punitive restoration to more varieties of offence-types and offenders bypassing the need for a trial in cases of noncompliance and further reducing potential sentencing costs. Nor should this be problematic: offenders receiving a suspended sentence in a punitive restoration conference meeting would retain access to legal representation throughout, must confirm any guilt without coercion and agree all terms presented to him or her at the conclusion of this meeting for committing offences where the alternative—through the traditional formal procedures of the courtroom—would include options that are at least as punitive. Note that one major difference is that only with punitive restoration would the possibility of hard treatment be an issue that must be agreed by the offender prior to its use. Let us consider two further instances where punitive restoration might justify some form of hard treatment. One is the idea of prison as a form of cooling off. Recall that imprisonment is often not the beginning of an offender’s socio-economic and legal difficulties, but rather their confirmation after an extended escalation. Imprisonment is characteristically disruptive. A consequence is that this can end already fragile support networks and render an individual’s road to sustainable prosperity tenuous. This is a significant problem for most offenders – but not for all. Perhaps for only a small, yet important minority the disruption from strongly negative support networks or difficult 17 personal circumstances can provide an opportunity for offenders to take a break where they might become open to personal transformation possible only through a prison-like environment. And this could be readily knowable as offenders are assessed by probation officers prior to any sentencing decision anyway to ensure any allocated prison place is suitable for any offender to be considered for hard treatment. 55 A second form of hard treatment that punitive restoration might incorporate is the idea of less time in prison with more intensity. This addresses on the fact most offenders serve short-term sentences without receiving any rehabilitative treatment. These treatments are costly and so prison wardens normally reserve expensive rehabilitative programmes for offenders serving more than one year in prison: this permits sufficient time for these programmes to be effective. However, these programmes are rarely intensive and—as already noted above—such high intensity programmes have been found to be effective at reducing drug and alcohol abuse, for example. 56 More such programmes would increase costs, but these might be accounted for by reducing the overall time spent in prison made possible by intensive rehabilitation programmes: the savings from the reduced time spent in prison overall could contribute to the increased costs of ensuring all inmates have access to the appropriate intensive rehabilitative programmes. Further savings might accrue through less reoffending on release if the programmes are successful. Punitive restoration might be objected to on the grounds that hard treatment, even for a few days, is a major curtailment of individual liberty which requires special safeguards only the formal procedures of the courtroom could satisfy. The problem with this objection is that only a relatively few cases are brought to trial. 57 Thus, the vast majority of cases are never heard in court and so victims and others affected by a crime are not permitted opportunities to gain a better understanding of why crimes occurred or receive an apology from their 18 offenders. It is hardly surprising to recall the widespread dissatisfaction many victims have with the traditional sentencing model. Punitive restoration is a concrete approach that can overcome this problem by providing greater opportunities for restorative meetings where victims express much higher satisfaction. 58 Restoration might not be for everybody. Restorative justice—as an alternative to traditional sentencing—is typically only available to offenders with little to no past criminal record. Punitive restoration attempts to create a space whereby more offenders can be brought into a restorative approach. While more punitive options can enable restoration and expand potential applicability, it is not argued that punitive restoration is appropriate for all crimes, including the most serious violent offences. If it was used, it might undermine its goal of winning over public confidence. Social reality matters and punitive restoration must “restore”—strong public opposition to its use could damage its ability to provide some form of restoration. Moreover, punitive restoration requires a time commitment. Not all victims or offenders will want to take part. Community members may not wish to participate. If punitive restoration is to work, then its conference format requires stakeholders to come together. It is my contention that since restorative conferences are shown to create more strongly positive experiences for victims and offenders than alternatives that their wider use could extend these experiences for more people. Over time punitive restoration might become more regularly practiced as the public becomes more supportive both through positive experiences and results. 59 Punitive restoration might also be objected to for a lack of any stated purpose beyond its endorsing the principle of stakeholding: this may help identify relevant participants, but which penal purpose should inform their sentencing outcomes? Punitive restoration is more than an improvement over alternative approaches to restorative justice, but a concrete 19 realization of a compelling perspective on penal purposes in practice. Punishment is often justified in reference to a justifying aim or purpose, such as retribution, deterrence or rehabilitation. Philosophers disagree about which among these is most preferable despite general agreement that hybrid combinations of two or more purposes often suffer from inconsistency. 60 This is illustrated well in Britain by s142 of the Criminal Justice Act 2003 which states that punishment must satisfy at least one of five penal purposes. This claim is restated in more recent sentencing guidelines. 61 However, there has been no attempt to claim how two or more such purposes can be brought together in a coherent, unified account. This “penal pluralism” may be legally possible, but its practicality remains questionable. 62 Punitive restoration is one form that a unified theory of punishment might take. This is because it is able to bring together multiple penal purposes within a coherent, unified framework. 63 For example, desert is satisfied because offenders must admit guilt without coercion prior to participation in a conference meeting. The penal goals of crime reduction, including the protection of the public, and enabling offender rehabilitation are achieved through targeting stakeholder needs arising from the meeting. The satisfaction of these goals is confirmed through the high satisfaction all participants report which suggests a general unanimity that the appropriate set of contractual stipulations have been agreed by all and the improvements in reducing reoffending suggest success in crime reduction and treatment consistent with deterrence and rehabilitation. 64 The argument here is not that any such unified theory is best or preferable to alternative theories. Instead, it is claimed punitive restoration is an example of how multiple penal principles might be addressed within a coherent, unified account. 65 Conclusion 20 Criminal justice policy faces the twin challenges of improving our crime reduction efforts while increasing public confidence. These challenges are exacerbated by the fact that at least some measures popular with the public, such as California’s “Three Strikes and You’re Out” law, are counterproductive to improving crime reduction. How to achieve more crime reduction without sacrificing public confidence? Restorative justice approaches offer a promising alternative to traditional sentencing with the potential to achieve these goals. Studies have found these approaches to yield significant improvements in combatting recidivism and greater satisfaction by participating victims at much reduced costs. Yet, restorative justice approaches suffer from several serious obstacles. These problems include the diversity of restorative approaches making it difficult to speak of any single approach leading to difficulties in making comparisons. Other problems include the limited applicability of restorative approaches to primarily youth offenders for less serious crimes, the limited flexibility of outcomes to exclude the possibility of imprisonment, the limited public confidence stemming from concerns restorative approaches are a soft option and a larger question about what is “restored” through restorative justice. Punitive restoration is a new and distinctive idea about restorative justice. It is modelled on an important principle of stakeholding which states that those who have a stake in penal outcomes should have a say about them. Punitive restoration brings relevant stakeholders together, including victims, offenders and members from the local community, to consider together the appropriate penal outcomes. Punitive restoration is restorative insofar as it aims to achieve the restoration of rights infringed or threatened by criminal offences. This is accomplished through recognition of the crime as a public wrong leading to a contractual arrangement agreed by stakeholders. Punitive restoration is punitive insofar as the available options for this agreement are more punitive than found in most restorative justice 21 approaches, such as the option of some form of hard treatment. This expansion of options within a restorative framework overcomes the many obstacles that limit the application, flexibility and public confidence of restorative alternatives. 66 Punitive restoration sheds new light on how we may meet the twin challenges of improving our efforts to reduce reoffending without sacrificing public confidence. This approach further demonstrates how restorative practices can be embedded deeper within the criminal justice system: by making restorative practices potentially more punitive we also may render the system less punitive overall. 67 Punitive restoration is an idea whose time has now come. 68 BIBLIOGRAPHY Ashworth, Andrew. “Sentencing.” In The Oxford Handbook of Criminology edited by Mike Maguire, Rod Morgan and Robert Reiner, 819—60. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994. Ashworth, Andrew. “Responsibilities, Rights and Restorative Justice,” British Journal of Criminology 42 (2002): 578—595. Ashworth, Andrew. Sentencing and Criminal Justice, 5 th ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010. Ashworth, Andrew and Mike Redmayne. The Criminal Process, 3 rd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005. Braithwaite, John. Restorative Justice and Responsive Regulation. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002. Braithwaite, John. “Setting Standards for Restorative Justice,” British Journal of Criminology 42 (2002): 563—77. Brooks, Thom. “The Right to Trial by Jury,” Journal of Applied Philosophy 21 (2004): 197— 212. Brooks, Thom. “Punishment: Political, Not Moral,” New Criminal Law Review 14 (2011): 427—38. Brooks, Thom. “Hegel and the Unified Theory of Punishment.” In Hegel’s Philosophy of Right edited by Thom Brooks, 103—23. Oxford: Blackwell, 2012. Brooks, Thom, ed. Hegel’s Philosophy of Right. Oxford: Blackwell, 2012. 22 Brooks, Thom. Punishment. New York: Routledge, 2012. Brooks, Thom. “On F. H. Bradley’s ‘Some Remarks on Punishment’,” Ethics 125 (2014): 223—5. Brooks, Thom. “Stakeholder Sentencing.” In Popular Punishment: On the Normative Significance of Public Opinion for Penal Theory edited by Jesper Ryberg and Julian Roberts, 183—203. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014. Brooks, Thom. “Criminal Harms.” In Law and Legal Theory edited by Thom Brooks, 149— 61. Boston: Brill, 2014. Brooks, Thom, ed. Law and Legal Theory. Boston: Brill, 2014. Brooks, Thom. “Punitive Restoration: Rehabilitating Restorative Justice,” Raisons Politiques (2015): 65—81. Brooks, Thom. “Justice as Stakeholding.” In Theorizing Justice: Critical Insights and Future Directions edited by Krushil Watene and Jay Drydyk, 111—27. New York: Rowman and Littlefield, 2016. Brooks, Thom. “Punitive Restoration: Giving the Public a Say on Sentencing.” In Democratic Theory and Mass Incarceration edited by Albert Dzur, Ian Loader and Richard Sparks, 140—61. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016. Brooks, Thom. “In Defence of Punishment and the Unified Theory of Punishment: A Reply,” Criminal Law and Philosophy 10 (2016): 629—38. Brown v. Plata, 563 U.S. (2011). Chapman, Jenny and Jacqui Smith. “Cutting Crime and Building Confidence.” In The Purple Book: A Progressive Future for Labour edited by Robert Philpott, 215—30. London: Biteback, 2011. Christie, Nils. “Conflicts as Property.” In Principled Sentencing: Readings on Theory and Policy edited by Andrew von Hirsch and Andrew Ashworth, 312—6. Oxford: Hart, 1998. Cullen, Francis T., Bonnie S. Fischer and Brandon K. Applegate, “Public Opinion about Punishment and Corrections,” Crime and Justice 37 (2000): 1—79. Cunneen, Chris and Carolyn Hoyle. Debating Restorative Justice. Oxford, Hart, 2010. Daly, Kathleen. “Mind the Gap: Restorative Justice in Theory and Practice.” In Restorative Justice and Criminal Justice: Competing or Reconcilable Paradigms? edited by Andrew von Hirsch, Julian V. Roberts, Anthony Bottoms, Kent Roach and Mara Schiff, 219—36. Oxford: Hart, 2003. 23 Daly, Marilyn, Craig T. Love, Donald S. Shepard, Cheryl B. Peterson, Karen L. White and Frank B. Hall. “Cost-Effectiveness of Connecticut’s In-Prison Substance Abuse Treatment,” Journal of Offender Rehabilitation 39 (2004): 69—92. Dignan, James. “Juvenile Justice, Criminal Courts and Restorative Justice.” In Handbook of Restorative Justice edited by Gerry Johnstone and Daniel W. Van Ness, 269—91. New York: Routledge, 2007. Durlauf, Steven N. and Daniel S. Nagin. “Imprisonment and Crime: Can Both Be Reduced?” Criminology and Public Policy 10 (2011): 13—54. Gardner, John. “Crime: In Proportion and in Perspective.” In Fundamentals of Sentencing Theory: Essays in Honour of Andrew von Hirsch edited by Andrew Ashworth and Martin Wasik, 31—52. Oxford: Clarendon, 1998. Joe, George W., Kevin Knight, D. Dwayne Simpson, Patrick M. Flynn, Janis T. Morey, Norma G. Bartholomew, Michele Staton Tindall, William M. Burdon, Elizabeth A. Hall, Steve S. Martin and Daniel J. O’Connell. “An Evaluation of Six Brief Interventions That Target Drug-Related Problems in Correctional Populations,” Journal of Offender Rehabilitation 51 (2012): 9—33. Johnstone, Gerry and Daniel W. Van Ness. “The Meaning of Restorative Justice.” In Handbook of Restorative Justice edited by Gerry Johnstone and Daniel W. Van Ness, 5—23. New York: Routledge, 2007. Liebling, Alison. Prisons and Their Moral Performance: A Study of Values, Quality and Prison Life. Oxford: Clarendon, 2006. Lippke, Richard L. Rethinking Imprisonment. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007. Llewellyn, Jennifer J. and Robert Howse. “Institutions for Restorative Justice: The South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission,” The University of Toronto Law Journal 49 (2009): 355—88. Marshall, T. F. Restorative Justice: An Overview, Home Office Occasional Paper. London: Home Office, 1999. Morrison, Brenda. “Schools and Restorative Justice.” In Handbook of Restorative Justice edited by Gerry Johnstone and Daniel W. Van Ness, 325—50. New York: Routledge, 2007. Parekh, Bhikhu. A New Politics of Identity: Political Principles for an Interdependent World. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2008. Perez, Deanna M. and Wesley G. Jennings. “Treatment Behind Bars: The Effectiveness of Prison-Based Therapy for Sex Offenders,” Journal of Crime and Justice 35 (2012): 435—50. Restorative Justice Council. What Does the Ministry of Justice RJ Research Tell Us? London: Restorative Justice Council, 2011. Roche, Declan. Accountability in Restorative Justice. Oxford: Clarendon, 2003. 24 Shapland, Joanna, Anne Atkinson, Helen Atkinson, Becca Chapman, E. Colledge, James Dignan, Marie Howes, Jennifer Johnstone, Gwen Robinson and Angela Sorsby. Restorative Justice in Practice: The Second Report from the Evaluation of Three Schemes. Centre for Criminological Research, University of Sheffield, 2006. Shapland, Joanna, Anne Atkinson, Helen Atkinson, Becca Chapman, James Dignan, Marie Howes, Jennifer Johnstone, Gwen Robinson and Angela Sorsby. Restorative Justice: The Views of Victims and Offenders. London: Ministry of Justice, 2007. Shapland, Joanna, Anne Atkinson, Helen Atkinson, James Dignan, Lucy Edwards, Jeremy Hibbert, Marie Howes, Jennifer Johnstone, Gwen Robinson and Angela Sorsby. Does Restorative Justice Affect Reconviction? The Fourth Report from the Evaluation of Three Schemes. London: Ministry of Justice, 2008. Shapland, Joanna, Gwen Robinson and Angela Sorsby. Restorative Justice in Practice: Evaluating What Works for Victims and Offenders. New York: Routledge, 2011. Tonry, Michael. “Less Imprisonment is No Doubt a Good Thing: More Policing is Not,” Criminology and Public Policy 10 (2011): 137—52. Towl, Graham J. “Drug-Misuse Intervention Work.” I Psychological Research in Prisons edited by Graham J. Towl. Oxford: Blackwell, 2006. Van Ness, Daniel W. “Prisons and Restorative Justice.” In Handbook of Restorative Justice edited by Gerry Johnstone and Daniel W. Van Ness, 312—24. New York: Routledge, 2007. Von Hirsch, Andrew and Andrew Ashworth. Proportionate Sentencing: Exploring the Principles. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005. Williams, Monica. “Beyond the Retributive Public: Governance and Public Opinion on Penal Policy,” Journal of Crime and Justice 35 (2011): 93—113 Zemring, Franklin E., Gordon Hawkins and Sam Kamin. Punishment and Democracy: Three Strikes and You’re Out in California. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001. 1 See Braithwaite, Restorative Justice and Responsive Regulation and Brooks, Punishment, 64—85. 2 Johnstone and Van Ness, “The Meaning of Restorative Justice.” 3 See Shapland, Robinson and Sorsby, Restorative Justice in Practice, 4 (“The restorative justice agenda . . . encompasses a very broad range of practices and approaches, such that a definitive definition has proven elusive”). See also Cunneen and Hoyle, Debating Restorative Justice. 4 See Morrison, “Schools and Restorative Justice.” 5 See van Ness, “Prisons and Restorative Justice.” 6 See Llewellyn and Howse, “Institutions for Restorative Justice.” 7 The focus is on restorative approaches that serve as an alternative to traditional sentencing in England and Wales, such as victim-offender mediation and restorative conferencing. This specification is important. There is a need to provide a more definitive and less contested model of restorative practices. The focus on one – admittedly significant – part of restorative practices is intended to help identify this new model, in part, by its distinctive form of application for England and Wales. This new model, punitive restoration, is discussed in this context, but it is not suggested that it cannot have a wider applicability to other jurisdictions. 8 Shapland, Robinson, Sorsby, Restorative Justice in Practice, 4. 25 9 Marshall, Restorative Justice. 10 Gardner, “Crime: In Proportion and in Perspective,” 31. 11 See Restorative Justice Council, “Best Practice.” 12 Offenders admitting guilt to a criminal offence for the purposes of engaging in victim-offender mediation or restorative conferencing and who either do not agree a restorative contract or fail to honour its terms in full need not admit guilt for this offence if the case is transferred to either a magistrates’ court or the Crown Court. This would appear to undermine the sincerity of the earlier admittance and it might be preferable to end this anomaly given that any admittance of guilt remains free of coercion and legal representation for offenders continues to be available although this policy suggestion is not considered further here. 13 See Shapland, et. al., Restorative Justice in Practice: The Second Report and Shapland, et. al., Restorative Justice: The Views of Victims, 27. 14 See Shapland, et. al., Does Restorative Justice Affect Reconviction? The Fourth Report and Restorative Justice Council, What Does the Ministry of Justice RJ Research Tell Us?. 15 Christie, “Conflicts as Property,” 314. 16 See Shapland, et al, Does Restorative Justice Affect Reconviction? 25-26. 17 See Shapland et al, Restorative Justice in Practice: The Second Report and Restorative Justice Council (n13). 18 I use restorative approaches and restorative practices interchangeably. 19 See Roche, Accountability in Restorative Justice. 20 See Brooks, Punishment, 173—188 and Dignan, “Juvenile Justice, Criminal Courts and Restorative Justice.” 21 See Brooks, Punishment, 67—68. 22 See Cullen, Fischer and Applegate, “Public Opinion about Punishment and Corrections,” and Zemring, Hawkins and Kamin, Punishment and Democracy. 23 See Durlauf and Nagin, “Imprisonment and Crime,” 28 and Brown v. Plata, 563 U.S. (2011). 24 See Williams, “Beyond the Retributive Public.” 25 See Ashworth, “Sentencing,” 822. 26 See Brooks, Punishment, 179—187. 27 See Durlauf and Nagin, “Imprisonment and Crime,” 14, 21-23. See also Lippke, Rethinking Imprisonment and Tonry, “Less Imprisonment is No Doubt a Good Thing,” 138, 140-41. 28 Braithwaite, Restorative Justice and Responsive Regulation. 29 Ibid. 30 Ashworth, Sentencing and Criminal Justice, 94. See Braithwaite, “Setting Standards for Restorative Justice.” 31 Ashworth, “Responsibilities, Rights and Restorative Justice,” 583. 32 See Parekh, A New Politics of Identity, 1, 21—26. 33 There is a further concern that there is a gap between the rhetoric of restorative justice approaches and their practical achievements that will not be considered here. See Kathleen Daly, “Mind the Gap: Restorative Justice in Theory and Practice.” 34 See Brooks, Punishment, 123, 132, 136, 142-43, 147-48 and Brooks, “Stakeholder Sentencing.” 35 Criminal offences infringe, or threaten the infringement, of rights. For example, theft is a violation of an individual’s right to property. Attempted offences are instances where the violation of rights is threatened. An attempted robbery is an instance where my rights to property and self are in jeopardy. Punishment as a restoration of rights recognises offences, including attempts, as the infringements, or threatened infringements, of rights that they are and it seeks to render their maintenance and future protection more secure by acknowledging just deserts and addressing underlying causes to rehabilitate if necessary and deter where possible. See Brooks, “Criminal Harms.” 36 See von Hirsch and Ashworth, Proportionate Sentencing, 110—111. 37 See Brooks, “Punitive Restoration: Rehabilitating Restorative Justice.” 38 See Brooks, “Justice as Stakeholding.” 39 Marshall, Restorative Justice. 40 See Braithwaite, Restorative Justice and Responsive Regulation, 11, 50, 55. 41 One study found that restorative conferences often include friends and family of the victim and of the offender, respectively, in 73% and 78% of cases examined. Parents were far more likely to attend restorative conferences (50% of offenders and 23% of victims) than partners (3% of offenders and 5% of victims). Shapland et al, Restorative Justice in Practice: The Second Report, 20. 42 See Shapland et al, Restorative Justice in Practice: The Second Report, 20. 43 See Brooks, “Punitive Restoration: Giving the Public a Say on Sentencing.” 44 See Restorative Justice Council, “Standards and Quality,” url: https://www.restorativejustice.org.uk/standards-and-quality. 45 An objection to this argument might be that the people rarely express their voices in the criminal justice system. With over 90% of trials in the US and UK never going to trial, victims rarely get much opportunity to 26 speak. It might be objected that making their voices heard more regularly is problematic because they should be heard no more than they are already. However, it should be countered that the minority of cases where their voices are heard – in both the jury box or witness stand – are the most serious cases. If the public’s voice matters for the most serious criminal cases, then it could be argued their voice should be heard in less serious cases as well. See Brooks, “The Right to Trial by Jury.” 46 See Restorative Justice Council, “Standards and Quality,” url: https://www.restorativejustice.org.uk/standards-and-quality. 47 See Liebling, Prisons and Their Moral Performance. 48 See Brooks, Punishment, 66-67, 73-75. On prison-based programmes designed to improve tackling drug and alcohol abuse, see Towl, “Drug-Misuse Intervention Work.” 49 See Perez and Jennings, “Treatment Behind Bars.” 50 See Chapman and Smith, “Cutting Crime and Building Confidence,” 215, 228. 51 See Ministry of Justice website. 52 See Joe, et. al., “An Evaluation of Six Brief Interventions.” 53 See Daly, et. al., “Cost-Effectiveness of Connecticut’s In-Prison Substance Abuse Treatment.” 54 The fact that a restorative contract might include hard treatment for any breach of contract need not mean offenders would be very unlikely to agree to such a contract. This is especially true for when failure to agree a contract would entail hard treatment anyway. 55 It is not suggested that probation officers always get this correct and no one has a crystal ball providing perfect predictions of the future. Yet officers may be able to ascertain where offenders are subjected to a strongly negative support network that could warrant a disruption as offered by punitive restoration, such as a cooling off period. 56 See Joe et. al., “An Evaluation of Six Brief Interventions” and Daly et. al., “Cost-Effectiveness of Connecticut’s In-Prison Substance Abuse Treatment.” 57 See Ashworth and Redmayne, The Criminal Process, 6—7. 58 It might be objected that some victims may see the opportunity to confront offenders as a chance to lavish anger and hostility. This is not what happens most often in practice. Yet even if it were so, the conference setting gives victims a voice but not the only say—and any contract (punitive or otherwise) must be acceptable by the offender to have any effect. Furthermore, contracts are not constructed in some anything goes fashion. There are guidelines to ensure that flexibility is restrained to ensure some consistency. 59 This is why it is claimed that if we want to find an approach that reduces crime more and increases public confidence then punitive restoration is a possibility we should consider because of its likely results and by the positive experiences by participants. Yet this is not about grafting punitive restoration onto an already criminogenic criminal justice system—it is the aim to help launch a shift towards more, not less, restorative justice within the criminal justice system thereby reducing the system’s criminogenic features. 60 See Brooks, Punishment, 89—100. 61 For example, see Sentencing Council, “Download a guideline,” url: http://www.sentencingcouncil.org.uk/publications/?type=publications&s=&cat=definitive- guideline&topic=&year. 62 On penal pluralism, see Brooks, “On F. H. Bradley’s ‘Some Remarks on Punishment” and Brooks, “In Defence of Punishment and the Unified Theory of Punishment.” 63 A unified theory of punishment may be constructed in different ways. The construction favoured here is to view crime as a harm to individual rights and punishment as “a response” to crime with the purpose of protecting and maintaining individual rights. This model rejects the view that penalties and hard treatment have different justificatory foundations, but rather they share a common justificatory source: the protection and maintenance of rights. The model of a unified theory can then better address the fact that penal outcomes are often multidimensional and include both financial and punitive elements. See Brooks, Punishment, 123—48 for a defence of the unified theory of punishment. 64 If satisfied, these conditions may be consistent with the idea of “empirical desert.” See Robinson, “Competing Conceptions of Modern Desert.” 65 See Brooks, “Punishment: Political, Not Moral” and Brooks, “Hegel and the Unified Theory of Punishment.” It is not argued here that other approaches could not also be consistent with a unified theory of punishment — only that punitive restoration is one illustration of it. 66 While it is suggested that expanding penal options would extend the applicability of punitive restoration, I am silent on how far this might extend. Yet whatever limits there might be and crimes that cannot be incorporated into a restorative framework for whatever reason, the claim is that more would be incorporated and not that all would or must be incorporated. 67 It has been suggested to me that this argument for punitive restoration is akin to a Trojan Horse strategy: restorative justice is dressed up in something more punitive, but if let through the thick impenetrable walls of the 27 criminal justice system there is a swift appearance of less punitiveness overall. This characterisation aptly captures a part of my strategy except that my aim in making criminal justice less punitive is not intended to be a surprise, but an achievement. I am grateful to Albert Dzur for this view. 68 Earlier versions of this paper were presented to the annual Howard League for Penal Reform conference at Keble College, Oxford; the Political Theory Workshop at Sciences Po-Paris; the Political Theory Colloquium at Harvard University’s JFK School of Government; the School of Social Sciences, Law and Business at Teesside University; the School of Public Policy at University College London; a Punishment and Prisons conference at Bowling Green State University and the City University of Hong Kong. I have benefited from comments from an anonymous referee for this journal and from Jacob Abolafia, Hilary Benn, Chris Bennett, Nick Bowes, Frances Crook, Albert Dzur, Douglas Husak, Sadiq Khan, Rick Lippke, Matt Matravers, Martha Nussbaum, Nicky Padfield, Bhikhu Parekh, Avia Pasternack, Andrei Poama, Harvey Redgrave, Julian Roberts, Paul Robinson, Michael Rosen, Avital Simhony, Astrid von Busekist and Albert Weale. work_6zx5mybaxjbv3bvrdyb534tixm ---- Global Justice Index Report Vol.:(0123456789) Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 https://doi.org/10.1007/s41111-020-00148-z 1 3 O R I G I N A L A R T I C L E Global Justice Index Report Yanfeng Gu1 · Xuan Qin1 · Zhongyuan Wang1 · Chunman Zhang1 · Sujian Guo1 Received: 3 April 2020 / Accepted: 17 April 2020 / Published online: 4 June 2020 © The Author(s) 2020, Corrected publication 2020 Abstract The Global Justice Index is a multiyear research project conducted at the Fudan-IAS to conceptualize and measure each country’s contribution to achieve greater global justice. In this study, we intend to provide our first-year achievements with the rank- ing of nation states at the global level from 2010 to 2017. This study comprises four main sections. In the introduction, we discuss the development of the conceptual framework and evaluative principles to justify our selection of dimensions and indica- tors for measurement. Next, in the section of methodology, we discuss the production, normalization, and aggregation of the raw data and the generation of the final results. The following section is the main findings, and we present the results through various visualization tools and provide regional comparisons for further analysis. In the last section, we discuss the applications and limitations of the index, and its potential fur- ther research trajectories. Keywords Global Justice Index · Indicators · Measurements · Methods · Country’s global ranking 1 Introduction The Global Justice Index is a multiyear research project conducted at the Fudan-IAS to conceptualize and measure each country’s contribution to achieve greater global justice. In this study, we intend to provide our first-year achievements with the ranking of nation states at the global level from 2010 to 2017. This study comprises four main sections. In the introduction, we discuss the development of the conceptual framework to justify our selection of dimensions and indicators for measurement. Next, in the section of methodology, we discuss the production, normalization, and aggregation of the raw data and the generation of the final results. The following section is the main findings, and we present the results through various visualization tools and provide * Sujian Guo sguo@fudan.edu.cn 1 Fudan Institute for Advanced Study in Social Sciences, Fudan University, Shanghai, China http://orcid.org/0000-0002-2846-0303 http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1007/s41111-020-00148-z&domain=pdf 254 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 regional comparisons for further analysis. In the last section, we discuss the applica- tions and limitations of the index, and its potential further research trajectories. Global justice is a broad concept composed of multilevel and multidimensional aspects belonging to both normative and empirical realities. A coherent, integrated theoretical framework that covers the normative basis and various empirical dimen- sions is, therefore, necessary to address some of the basic and important questions under study. Our study began with the conceptualization of global justice and was completed based on a theoretical paper on “Conceptualizing and Measuring Global Justice: Theories, Concepts, Principles and Indicators,” coauthored by the project leader, Sujian Guo, et  al., published in Fudan Journal of the Humanities and Social Sciences (Vol. 12, No. 4, 2019). The paper  discusses theories, concepts, evaluative principles, and methodologies related to the study of global justice. In the paper above, we attempt to clarify how to conceptualize global justice, how indicators can be selected and theoretically justified, and how those indicators can be conceptually consistent with the concept of global justice. Through the syn- thesis of multiple theories and intellectual traditions in various cultural and political contexts, we conceptualize global justice from three main approaches—rights-based, goods-based, and virtue-based—to develop a theoretical framework with a norma- tive basis for the following measurement. Rights-based conceptualization focuses on the basic principles, rules, and sources of legitimacy of justice (Universal Declaration of Human Rights 1948; Rawls 1971, 1999). Goods-based conceptualization concen- trates on the material and institutional supports that the governments or institutions are obliged to provide (Arneson 1989; Freeman 2006; Nussbaum 2006, 2011; Richard- son 2006). And virtue-based conceptualization regards justice as a virtue that an indi- vidual is willing to pursue rather than a regulation an individual is forced to comply with Mo (2003). The relationship between the three approaches of conceptualization is interdependent rather than separate, which indicates three interrelated components of a holistic whole. Additionally, the three approaches are complementary rather than competing, with the rights-based conceptualization forming the basic structure as the “bones”, the goods-based conceptualization providing substantial material supports as the “muscles”, and the virtue-based conceptualization emphasizing personal motiva- tion and internalized willingness as the “heart” (Guo et al. 2019). Based on the aforementioned theoretical framework, we propose two evaluative prin- ciples to further bridge the gap between theories and practice to determine and justify our selection of issue areas for evaluation. We call the two principles Common but Dif- ferentiated and Respective Capabilities (CBDR-RC) and Cosmopolitan but Due-diligent Responsibilities (CDDR). CBDR-RC addresses the issues “for which no single nation state can be held directly accountable or responsible, matters that can only be tackled through the globally concerted efforts of all stakeholders” (Guo et al. 2019). For exam- ple, it is the responsibility of all to protect the climate system and ecological balance, and environmental protection is a task that cannot be handled by one country on its own. The principle of CBDR-RC, first adopted by the United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change and reaffirmed in the Rio Declaration on Environment and Develop- ment, combines normative legitimacy and historical rationality. Although it was a princi- ple that first aimed to determine the responsibilities of each country for climate change, it 255 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 has been expanded to the other global justice areas such as combating transnational crime and global peacekeeping. The second principle, CDDR, addresses that “all-nation-states are morally obligated to provide cosmopolitan aid, in which context the least advantaged will have a due-dili- gent responsibility” (Guo et al. 2019). This principle is based on the concept of “mutual accountability” proposed in the Paris Declaration on Aid Effectiveness, adopted in 2005 at the Second High-Level Forum on Aid Effectiveness to promote a better cooperation between different actors in aid and development. This principle views such obligations as part of domestic affairs, such as anti-poverty and education policy, in the context of which the nation states are expected to provide material and institutional assistance to their citi- zenry within their territories. According to the principles of CBDR-RC and CDDR, we determine two clusters of global justice issue areas for practical measurement. Those issue areas that follow the principle of CBDR-RC are (1) climate change (global warming), (2) peacekeeping, (3) humanitarian aid, (4) terrorism and armed conflicts, and (5) cross-national criminal police cooperation, and those belonging to the principle of CDDR are (6) anti-poverty, (7) education, (8) public health, and (9) the protection of women and children. In the fol- lowing sections, we present the more practical part of operationalization and measure- ment to assess the performance and contribution of each nation state to promote justice at the global level. 2 Methodology: Construction of the Global Justice Index In this study, we classify our data into four levels: indicators, dimensions, categories, and issues. The first and the bottom levels of our data provide the information on indicators, which is our raw data. The second level is named dimensions, which usually comprises several related indicators. The third level is categories and comprises several related dimensions. And the last level is the issue index, usually calculated based on two catego- ries: contribution and performance. The global justice index is calculated as follows. 2.1 First Step: Convert Indicator Indices To ensure comparability between indicators, we use the following two formulas to con- vert the raw data into comparable indicators: (1)iiij = actual valueij − min (actual value.j) max (actual value.j) − min (actual value.j) + 1 (2)iiij = max (actual value.j) − actual valueij max (actual value.j) − min (actual value.j) + 1 i ∈ {1, 2, ⋯ 192}, j ∈ {2010, 2011, ⋯ 2017}, 256 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 where actual valueij indicates the actual value of an indicator in country i in year j. min (actual value.j) is the minimum value of an indicator among all countries in year j, and max (actual value.j) is the maximum value of an indicator among all countries in year j. If an indicator positively relates to global justice, the first formula is used to convert the raw data; if not, the second formula is used. 2.2 Second Step: Population‑Based Weighting Consciously, countries with various populations should make different efforts to raise the welfare of their people to the same level. If one compares with the efforts that countries make to raise the welfare of their people; therefore, we weight indicators based on popu- lation size. Proceed as follows: First, calculate the weighted average of an indicator as per the following formula: iimj is the weighted average of an indicator. iiij is the actual value of an indicator in country i in year j. populationij is the population size of country i in year j. Second, calculate the weight of each country on an indicator as follows: ssij is the weight of country i in year j. Third, calculate the score for an indicator in country i in year j as follows: where IIij is the score of an indicator in country i in year j. We use IIij to further cal- culate the dimension global justice. 2.3 Third Step: Calculate the Scores of Both Dimension Indices and Category Indices For each variable, we calculate the score of the variable index as follows: where VIij is the score of the variable index. Similarly, we use VIij to further calculate the score of dimension indices as follows: (3)iimj = ∑ iiij × populationij ∑ populationij . (4)ssij = (iiij − iim) × populationij. (5)IIij = ssij − min (ss.j) max (ss.j) − min (ss.j) + 1 , (6)VIij = n √ ∏ k IIijk, (7)DIij = n √ ∏ k VIijk. 257 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 2.4 Fourth Step: Calculate the Score of the Issue Index We use DIij to further calculate the score of each issue in county i in year j as follows: 2.5 Last Step: Calculate Global Justice Index We use the following formula to calculate the score of the global justice index in coun- try i in year j: where GJij is the score of global justice in country i and year j. ISIijk is the score of issue k in country i in year j. 3 Findings In this section, we will report the results of the measurement and country ranking in the identified nine issue areas related to global justice based on available data sources. We will present dimensions, variables, indicators, and data sources, and evaluate and rank the countries in terms of performance and contribution. We then present the results through various visualization tools and provide regional comparisons for fur- ther analysis. 3.1 Issue 1: Climate Change This report studies countries’ efforts to promote global justice from the perspectives of climate change, peacekeeping, and other issues. Climate change and peacekeeping are issues for which no single actor can be held directly accountable or responsible. They are issue areas that can only be addressed through the globally concerted efforts of all stakeholders. Global warming is a real, disastrous phenomenon, with many destructive effects. Scientists have concluded that human influence is most likely the dominant cause of the observed warming since the mid-twentieth century. If all countries remain passive about climate change, the situation will worsen, with dramatic consequences globally. Alternately, if countries cooperate and coordinate to combat global warming, the negative impacts of climate change on this plane would be significantly alleviated. (8)ISIij = n √ ∏ k DIijk. (9)GJij = 9 √ ∏ k ISIijk, 258 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 3.1.1 Dimensions and Indicators Today, countries attempt to resolve climate change problems by, for example, reducing CO2 emission, planting more trees, and supporting clean and renewable energy. Thus, our dimensions of climate change include CO2 emission, energy use, forestry, and electricity (Table  1). We have selected more than ten indicators derived from four dimensions. In the energy use dimension, our indicators include energy use per capita, energy use per 1000 dollars of gross domestic product, and fossil fuel energy consumption. In the CO2 emission dimension, four indicators are used: CO2 emissions from gas, liquid, solid, and fuel consumption per capita and CO2 intensity per capita. The forestry dimension has two indicators. The electric- ity dimension has four indicators: electricity production from hydroelectric sources, oil, gas and coal sources, renewable sources, and nuclear sources. These data are all available for 195 countries from the World Bank. However, the time span is from 2000 to 2014 (2010–2014 is more important for our research purpose). We under- stand that these four dimensions and the indicators selected for this study may be not the most ideal, but they can to a large extent measure countries’ efforts to solve climate change problems. 3.1.2 Results In this section, we present the ranking results of the countries’ contributions to global justice from a climate change perspective (Table 2). Table 2 shows 5 years of results from 2010 to 2014 in 195 countries. Table  2 shows the countries’ climate-change ranking from 2010 to 2014. Due to the missing value problem, some countries (e.g., Afghanistan, Zambia, Zimba- bwe, and Monaco) do not have full data for the year 2014. However, 116 coun- tries in Table 2 have full data. In general, we observe that developed countries have performed relatively better than developing countries in terms of promoting global justice from a climate change perspective. In most cases, countries’ rankings have been stable from 2010 to 2014. Figure  1 shows that the top ten countries in 2014 are Sweden, Brazil, Gabon, Finland, Paraguay, Costa Rica, Congo, Democratic Republic of the Congo, Cam- bodia, and Cameroon. Sweden and Finland are developed countries and the remain- ing eight countries are developing countries. Brazil, Costa Rica, and Paraguay are South American countries. Cambodia is an Asian country. Gabon, Democratic Republic of the Congo, Cameroon, and Congo are African countries. China ranks 87th in 2014, and the United States ranks 73rd in 2014. This finding implies that the two largest economies must make more contributions despite the progress achieved prior to 2014. 259 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Ta bl e 1 D at a on c lim at e ch an ge C at eg or y D im en si on In di ca to r D at a so ur ce C ov er ag e Pe rf or m an ce E ne rg y us e E ne rg y us e (k g of o il eq ui va le nt p er c ap ita ) E ne rg y us e (k g of o il eq ui va le nt ) p er $ 10 00 G D P (c on st an t 2 01 1P PP ) Fo ss il fu el e ne rg y co ns um pt io n (% o f t ot al ) W or ld B an k 19 5 (2 01 0– 20 14 ) C O 2 em is si on C O 2 em is si on s fr om g as fu el c on su m pt io n (k t) p er c ap ita C O 2 em is si on s fr om li qu id fu el c on su m pt io n (k t) p er c ap ita C O 2 em is si on s fr om s ol id fu el c on su m pt io n (k t) p er c ap ita C O 2 in te ns ity (k g pe r k g of o il eq ui va le nt e ne rg y us e) p er c ap ita W or ld B an k Fo re st ry Fo re st a re a (% o f l an d ar ea ) Fo re st a re a (k m 2 ) W or ld B an k E le ct ri ci ty E le ct ri ci ty p ro du ct io n fr om h yd ro el ec tr ic s ou rc es (% o f t ot al ) E le ct ri ci ty p ro du ct io n fr om o il, g as a nd c oa l s ou rc es (% o f t ot al ) E le ct ri ci ty p ro du ct io n fr om re ne w ab le s ou rc es , e xc lu di ng h yd ro el ec tr ic (% o f to ta l) E le ct ri ci ty p ro du ct io n fr om n uc le ar s ou rc es (% o f t ot al ) W or ld B an k 260 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 Table 2 Country ranking in the climate change aspect of promoting global justice Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 Sweden 2 2 2 2 1 Brazil 3 3 3 3 2 Gabon 8 9 5 4 3 Finland 15 12 8 7 4 Paraguay 5 7 6 5 5 Costa Rica 6 8 7 8 6 Congo 9 6 9 9 7 Democratic Republic of the Congo 7 4 10 10 8 Cambodia 29 26 15 11 9 Cameroon 11 10 11 12 10 United Republic of Tanzania 10 14 16 16 11 Nepal 12 13 13 14 12 Myanmar 4 5 4 6 13 France 20 17 17 17 14 Slovenia 26 24 24 23 15 Mozambique 16 11 12 13 16 Suriname 18 19 20 18 17 Switzerland 22 21 21 21 18 Guatemala 13 16 14 15 19 Ghana 17 18 19 20 20 Angola 14 15 18 19 21 Estonia 24 22 22 24 22 Colombia 23 20 23 26 23 Slovakia 34 32 31 29 24 Montenegro 21 27 25 22 25 Kenya 31 29 32 35 26 Austria 41 40 34 33 27 Albania 30 28 26 27 28 Peru 19 23 27 28 29 Latvia 40 39 28 31 30 Panama 32 35 30 32 31 Ethiopia 48 33 35 36 32 Honduras 27 25 29 30 33 Nicaragua 42 46 38 34 34 Sri Lanka 25 30 37 25 35 Norway 50 38 36 44 36 Spain 46 48 44 37 37 Uruguay 38 51 60 47 38 New Zealand 37 36 41 41 39 Cote d’Ivoire 35 34 40 45 40 Portugal 47 50 52 43 41 Georgia 28 41 45 39 42 261 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Table 2 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 Romania 53 58 57 48 43 Croatia 59 64 59 53 44 Hungary 60 60 55 52 45 Tajikistan 36 37 42 40 46 Indonesia 45 44 47 46 47 Senegal 44 43 43 50 48 Ecuador 49 47 46 55 49 El Salvador 39 45 48 49 50 Bulgaria 58 62 53 51 51 Namibia 54 52 50 56 52 Canada 64 61 54 58 53 Togo 77 53 51 57 54 Lithuania 76 71 69 61 55 Czechia 69 68 64 63 56 Philippines 56 55 56 59 57 Republic of Korea 62 59 62 66 58 Belgium 72 63 63 62 59 Bolivia (Plurinational State of) 52 54 58 60 60 Nigeria 55 56 61 64 61 Russian Federation 65 65 65 65 62 Germany 63 66 66 68 63 Italy 82 81 73 69 64 Denmark 86 80 71 74 65 Benin 66 67 67 67 66 Bosnia and Herzegovina 73 85 81 76 67 Chile 75 73 70 71 68 Japan 43 57 68 70 69 Republic of North Macedonia 68 75 79 73 70 Dominican Republic 78 76 74 75 71 India 70 70 72 72 72 United States of America 85 82 76 77 73 Malaysia 80 79 77 82 74 Pakistan 79 77 78 78 75 Serbia 87 91 86 88 76 Greece 90 92 90 83 77 Mexico 83 84 83 84 78 Kyrgyzstan 74 74 82 79 79 Armenia 61 72 80 80 80 Niger 81 83 84 85 81 United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland 99 94 92 86 82 Haiti 71 78 75 81 83 262 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 Table 2 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 Ukraine 96 89 91 89 84 Thailand 88 86 85 87 85 Jamaica 91 90 87 90 86 China 94 95 93 92 87 Mauritius 84 88 89 91 88 Poland 98 98 96 96 89 Bangladesh 92 93 95 95 90 Botswana 89 87 88 93 91 Turkey 93 96 94 94 92 Argentina 97 97 97 97 93 Ireland 103 102 100 100 94 Morocco 95 99 98 98 95 Belarus 100 100 99 99 96 Iceland 101 101 101 101 97 Cyprus 111 112 105 103 98 Australia 108 108 108 107 99 Netherlands 107 106 102 108 100 Brunei Darussalam 114 110 102 101 Tunisia 104 104 103 106 102 Iraq 106 107 107 109 103 Singapore 112 110 104 110 104 Republic of Moldova 110 109 111 104 105 Azerbaijan 102 103 109 111 106 Lebanon 105 105 106 105 107 Israel 115 116 116 114 108 South Africa 113 111 112 112 109 Egypt 109 113 113 113 110 Mongolia 117 118 115 116 111 Jordan 116 117 117 118 112 Luxembourg 126 127 124 121 113 Algeria 118 119 118 120 114 Iran (Islamic Republic of) 119 120 119 119 115 Kazakhstan 122 123 122 123 116 Libya 121 122 121 122 117 Malta 123 124 123 124 118 United Arab Emirates 126 126 126 119 Saudi Arabia 124 125 125 125 120 Oman 125 128 127 121 Kuwait 129 127 128 122 Bahrain 130 123 Trinidad and Tobago 127 131 128 129 124 Qatar 130 125 263 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 3.2 Issue 2: Peacekeeping Similar to climate change, peacekeeping has no single actor that can be held directly accountable or responsible. UN peacekeeping is an attempt, after peace has been negotiated or imposed by internal and external players, to address the causes of current hostility and to build local capacity for conflict resolution. A global effort is required to maintain international peace and security. All countries—big and small, developed and developing—can participate and make contributions. Table 2 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 Eritrea 67 69 Uzbekistan 120 121 120 117 Venezuela (Bolivarian Republic of) 57 49 49 54 Viet Nam 51 42 39 42 Yemen 114 115 114 115 Zambia 1 1 1 1 Zimbabwe 33 31 33 38 Fig. 1 2014 index ranking of climate change on a world map 264 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 3.3 Dimensions and Indicators To measure a country’s effort to promote global justice by contributing to UN peace- keeping, our dimensions include personnel contribution and financial contribution (Table 2). The personnel contribution dimension is measured by the troops and police contribution indicator. The financial contribution dimension is measured by the finan- cial donation contribution. Our data source is the United Nations peacekeeping official website and International Peace Institute. Approximately 120 countries are studied in this research. The time span for our study is from 2010 to 2017 (Table 3). 3.3.1 Results In this section, we present the ranking result of countries’ contributions to global jus- tice from the peacekeeping perspective (Table 4). Table 4 shows countries’ ranking in UN peacekeeping from 2010 to 2017. In gen- eral, Bangladesh, Ethiopia, India, Nepal, Pakistan, Rwanda, the United States, and China have made tremendous contributions to UN peacekeeping; among these coun- tries, China and the United States are UN security council members. Although India is not a UN security council member, it is a regional and rising power. Bangladesh is a small country, but is a top five country in its contributions to UN peacekeeping. Based on these data, countries’ willingness is more important than capacity in terms of deter- mining how much contribution one country attempts to make toward peacekeeping (Fig. 2). In 2017, the top five countries are the United States, Ethiopia, India, Bangladesh, and Pakistan. The United States provided most funding to UN peacekeeping, and Ethiopia provided most troops and police for UN peacekeeping activities. Most of the developed countries are among the top 100, and some developing countries, especially those in Africa, did not contribute much. 3.4 Issue 3: Humanitarian Aid Humanitarian aid is short-term assistance, including material and logistic assistance, delivered to individuals in need. Usually, humanitarian aid is provided in response to natural disasters and emergencies. In these cases, providing help to save lives, reduce Table 3 Data on peacekeeping Category Dimension Indicator Data source Coverage Contribution Personnel contribution Troops and police UN Peacekeeping Website International Peace Institute 129 (2010–2017) Financial contribution Donation UN Peacekeeping Website International Peace Institute 120 (2010–2017) 265 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Table 4 Country ranking in the peacekeeping aspect of promoting global justice Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 United States of America 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 Ethiopia 19 15 5 5 5 3 2 2 India 4 4 4 4 3 5 3 3 Bangladesh 3 2 2 2 2 2 5 4 Pakistan 2 3 3 3 4 4 4 5 China 11 12 7 9 8 7 6 6 Rwanda 13 13 8 7 6 6 7 7 Nepal 9 9 11 8 7 8 8 8 Senegal 20 21 19 16 13 11 9 9 Egypt 6 7 10 14 15 20 14 10 Japan 7 6 9 10 10 9 10 11 France 8 8 12 12 11 10 13 12 Indonesia 23 23 23 23 26 15 15 13 Ghana 14 17 14 13 12 12 11 14 Germany 16 16 16 17 17 16 19 15 Burkina Faso 34 30 32 27 22 19 12 16 United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland 15 14 17 18 18 17 20 17 United Republic of Tanzania 32 27 26 21 19 22 18 18 Italy 10 11 15 15 14 14 17 19 Morocco 24 24 24 24 21 21 22 20 Nigeria 5 5 6 6 9 13 16 21 Spain 18 18 22 25 28 27 28 22 Chad 89 89 88 40 33 34 26 23 Togo 38 41 40 28 27 25 23 24 South Africa 22 22 21 20 20 23 24 25 Russian Federation 28 32 29 32 34 35 30 26 Republic of Korea 25 25 25 29 30 31 31 27 Uruguay 17 20 20 19 24 29 27 28 Niger 45 38 30 26 25 24 21 29 Brazil 21 19 18 22 23 28 25 30 Cameroon 76 76 72 80 29 18 32 31 Zambia 37 45 63 70 75 50 39 32 Mauritania 157 158 138 136 93 74 40 33 Mongolia 50 80 45 35 36 39 38 34 Canada 26 26 28 33 79 86 36 35 Benin 27 33 34 30 31 30 29 36 Malawi 68 42 35 41 40 40 37 37 Guinea 86 87 90 73 67 46 42 38 Jordan 12 10 13 11 16 26 33 39 Malaysia 30 29 27 34 37 41 43 40 Burundi 88 79 77 69 47 32 35 41 Cambodia 80 61 57 52 43 42 44 42 266 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 Table 4 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Netherlands 39 40 42 46 35 33 41 43 Australia 36 35 39 39 42 44 46 44 Fiji 60 59 58 48 41 45 47 45 Ireland 52 48 43 45 49 52 52 46 Sweden 46 49 52 54 53 47 48 47 Uganda 66 88 94 93 96 100 49 48 Sri Lanka 29 28 31 31 32 43 51 49 Argentina 33 31 33 36 38 48 55 50 Congo 145 153 153 156 58 38 45 51 Gabon 143 142 144 143 69 53 56 52 Ukraine 53 56 46 43 44 49 50 53 Finland 59 62 59 51 46 51 54 54 Austria 40 39 38 42 50 54 57 55 Switzerland 47 50 54 55 55 57 60 56 Gambia 51 52 50 53 54 61 61 57 Norway 49 55 56 57 56 56 59 58 Portugal 44 47 53 71 73 71 77 59 Serbia 94 91 82 72 66 60 62 60 Saudi Arabia 64 65 68 68 74 73 66 61 Peru 54 54 49 50 51 62 58 62 Belgium 41 44 47 49 52 59 63 63 Denmark 48 51 62 62 63 63 67 64 Tunisia 58 95 92 67 76 69 65 65 Kenya 35 36 37 37 39 36 34 66 Chile 43 43 44 47 48 55 53 67 El Salvador 79 82 83 79 83 72 69 68 Slovakia 62 64 66 64 68 67 71 69 Guatemala 57 57 60 58 59 64 68 70 Greece 56 58 61 59 64 65 72 71 Turkey 42 46 41 44 60 66 70 72 United Arab Emirates 71 70 67 66 71 70 74 73 Djibouti 98 96 95 74 72 75 75 74 Cote d’Ivoire 69 68 69 60 62 76 124 75 Israel 67 69 71 76 78 78 78 76 Singapore 70 71 73 78 82 84 79 77 Paraguay 83 66 65 63 70 77 76 78 Yemen 63 60 55 56 61 58 64 79 Mexico 65 67 75 77 81 81 83 80 Hungary 73 73 74 75 77 79 81 81 Czechia 90 84 76 81 84 85 82 82 Romania 78 81 80 83 86 82 80 83 Sierra Leone 61 53 51 65 80 89 88 84 267 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Table 4 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Zimbabwe 75 75 85 82 89 92 85 85 Philippines 31 34 36 38 45 68 73 86 New Zealand 74 74 79 85 87 90 86 87 Poland 77 78 78 84 85 87 87 88 Kuwait 84 83 84 88 91 93 89 89 Qatar 93 93 87 90 94 94 91 90 Liberia 157 158 155 103 97 97 95 91 Estonia 111 108 108 108 110 98 94 92 Mali 81 77 81 87 90 88 90 93 Bolivia (Plurinational State of) 55 63 64 61 65 83 107 94 Colombia 95 99 98 97 101 107 96 95 Namibia 87 86 89 94 88 91 92 96 Slovenia 92 90 91 95 98 96 98 97 Bosnia and Herzegovina 101 100 96 92 95 99 99 98 Thailand 82 37 48 96 99 80 97 99 Bhutan 158 159 162 163 149 112 103 100 Brunei Darussalam 105 97 99 99 105 102 102 101 Honduras 115 113 112 113 100 95 93 102 Armenia 151 150 140 142 125 103 101 103 Venezuela (Bolivarian Republic of) 102 104 97 98 103 101 104 104 Oman 114 112 100 100 106 106 106 105 Iran (Islamic Republic of) 106 106 103 104 109 110 105 106 Madagascar 91 92 93 89 102 108 100 107 Croatia 72 72 70 91 104 104 108 108 Kyrgyzstan 104 107 105 101 107 111 110 109 Luxembourg 96 98 102 102 108 109 109 110 Samoa 112 117 110 112 112 116 113 111 Kazakhstan 118 120 116 121 124 115 111 112 Cyprus 107 105 106 107 111 113 112 113 Algeria 116 110 111 110 114 118 115 114 Dominican Republic 129 127 132 130 131 136 132 115 Lithuania 119 116 119 117 116 121 120 116 Cuba 125 124 128 127 133 131 131 117 Bahrain 113 111 113 114 118 119 116 118 Ecuador 85 85 86 86 92 105 114 119 Libya 99 101 109 111 115 114 117 120 Viet Nam 132 133 133 133 136 127 121 121 Belarus 129 125 120 116 122 124 122 122 Latvia 126 126 127 126 132 130 126 123 Republic of Moldova 121 118 118 115 119 120 118 124 Democratic Republic of the Congo 109 102 104 109 57 37 84 125 Bulgaria 124 122 121 122 126 126 127 126 268 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 Table 4 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Iraq 139 138 129 128 134 132 123 127 Iceland 108 109 115 118 121 123 125 128 Montenegro 128 123 122 123 127 133 129 129 Costa Rica 131 132 136 135 141 140 137 130 Malta 122 119 124 124 129 128 128 131 Solomon Islands 157 158 161 163 166 164 141 132 Central African Republic 100 94 101 106 117 135 163 133 Trinidad and Tobago 120 115 117 119 123 125 130 134 Bahamas 123 121 125 125 130 129 131 135 Azerbaijan 144 141 134 134 140 138 134 136 Papua New Guinea 154 151 143 138 150 143 129 137 Monaco 144 141 130 129 135 134 136 138 Lebanon 132 133 133 133 138 137 138 139 Georgia 150 149 151 154 157 154 135 140 Panama 138 137 139 140 146 147 139 141 Andorra 130 131 134 134 140 138 140 142 Myanmar 153 153 153 156 159 146 133 143 Turkmenistan 134 134 145 144 151 149 143 144 Syrian Arab Republic 136 135 137 137 144 142 144 145 Uzbekistan 148 147 147 147 154 153 145 146 Republic of North Macedonia 140 139 141 141 148 148 146 147 Guinea-Bissau 127 129 161 151 147 151 147 148 San Marino 144 141 147 147 154 153 149 149 Barbados 137 136 146 146 153 152 150 150 Botswana 141 140 123 145 152 150 150 150 Jamaica 103 103 107 120 113 117 142 151 Mauritius 146 146 148 149 156 155 151 152 Albania 97 130 150 152 142 141 153 153 Suriname 153 153 154 157 160 158 154 154 Cabo Verde 156 157 160 162 163 161 162 155 Mozambique 135 144 142 150 155 162 148 156 Angola 151 150 153 156 159 157 155 157 Democratic People’s Republic of Korea 149 148 152 155 158 156 155 157 Equatorial Guinea 152 152 153 156 159 157 155 157 Sudan 151 150 153 156 159 157 155 157 Timor-Leste 157 154 126 139 137 139 152 158 Nicaragua 153 153 156 158 161 159 156 159 Tajikistan 117 114 114 105 120 159 156 159 Afghanistan 154 155 157 159 162 160 158 160 Antigua and Barbuda 152 152 154 157 160 158 158 160 Vanuatu 110 158 161 148 128 122 119 161 Eswatini 153 153 156 158 161 159 160 162 269 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 suffering, and maintain human dignity is a vital aspect of the global justice agenda. As a result, we include this humanitarian aid in our global justice index and measure each country’s efforts to provide humanitarian aid by evaluating their financial contribution to global humanitarian affairs. 3.4.1 Indicators We use ten indicators to measure each country’s efforts toward humanitarian aid. These ten indicators are food, health, water, emergency response, early recovery, coordination, education, protection, agriculture, and others, and indicate the sectors that receive the humanitarian donation of each country. The last indicator, “others,” denotes the part of the donation without a designated use. We count the humanitar- ian donation from each country to UN departments, nongovernmental organizations, and other relevant organizations such as the World Food Program, the World Health Table 4 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Guyana 156 157 160 162 165 163 160 162 Maldives 157 158 160 162 165 163 160 162 Haiti 155 156 159 161 164 162 161 163 Lao People’s Democratic Republic 157 158 160 162 165 163 161 163 Saint Kitts and Nevis 156 157 159 161 163 161 161 163 South Sudan 158 159 158 160 163 161 161 163 Belize 156 157 160 162 165 163 162 164 Dominica 156 157 160 162 165 163 162 164 Grenada 133 128 149 153 145 144 159 164 Marshall Islands 156 157 160 162 165 163 162 164 Micronesia (Federated States of) 156 157 160 162 165 163 162 164 Nauru 156 157 160 162 165 163 162 164 Palau 142 143 135 132 143 163 162 164 Saint Lucia 156 157 160 162 165 163 162 164 Saint Vincent and the Grenadines 156 157 160 162 165 163 162 164 Seychelles 152 152 159 161 164 162 162 164 Tonga 156 157 160 162 165 163 162 164 Comoros 157 158 161 163 166 164 163 165 Eritrea 157 158 161 163 166 164 163 165 Kiribati 157 158 161 163 166 164 163 165 Lesotho 147 145 131 131 139 145 157 165 Sao Tome and Principe 157 158 161 163 166 164 163 165 Somalia 157 158 161 163 166 164 163 165 Tuvalu 157 158 161 163 166 164 163 165 270 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 Organization (WHO), and the International Federation of Red Cross and Red Crescent Societies. Data are obtained from the Financial Tracking Service database, managed by the UN Office for the Coordination of Humanitarian Affairs. It “aims to present a complete picture of all international humanitarian funding flows”, such that it “sup- ports the transparency and accountability of the humanitarian system and facilitates resource mobilization”1 (Table 5). Fig. 2 2017 index ranking of peacekeeping on a world map Table 5 Data on humanitarian aid Issue area Indicator Source Coverage Humanitarian aid Food Financial Tracking Service 181 (2010–2017) Health Water Emergency Response Early Recovery Coordination Education Protection Agriculture Other 1 Please check https ://fts.unoch a.org/conte nt/about -fts-1 for more information about FTS. https://fts.unocha.org/content/about-fts-1 271 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 3.4.2 Results Data of the past 10 years show that the US has always been the nation who contributes the most. The traditional liberal democracies, such as Britain, Germany, Canada, The Netherlands, France, and Australia, have a dominantly high proportion of being one of the top 20 contributors. Kuwait and Saudi Arabia, high-income economies with the world’s largest oil reserves, have been in the top 20 contributors as well. China is the nation who contributes the most in Asia and ranks 16 in 2017, followed by Japan, Rus- sia, and India, who have been among the top 50 contributors in the past 10 years. Afri- can and Central Asian countries with poor economies rank relatively low (Table 6). This regional difference is more obvious on a map. Figure  3 presents a map of the humanitarian assistance contribution from each country in 2017. A darker color denotes a higher rank. On the map, the countries in East Europe, North America, and Australia are covered with a darker color and contributed the most, and countries in Africa, Central Asia, and Southeast Asia are covered with a relatively lighter color. 3.5 Issue 4: Terrorism and Armed Conflicts Terrorism and armed conflicts are major challenges to global justice. The efforts by global partners to combat terrorist violence and conflict threats are a significant aspect of the global justice agenda. Global justice can improve if nation states increase their efforts to manage cross-national conflicts and domestic terrorist threats. In the past decade, the number of violent conflicts and terrorist attacks worldwide has increased. Thus, the international community and individual countries have a duty to prioritize conflict management and terrorism governance on their agenda and act to resolve the problems identified. 3.5.1 Dimensions and Indicators Using data from highly respected sources, our project measures each country’s influ- ence on global justice in the issue area of terrorism and armed conflicts by focusing on two categories: performance and contribution. Performance refers to the extent to which a country is involved in armed conflicts and terrorism attacks. This category is measured using five thematic indictors: (1) number of conflicts, (2) number of wars, (3) number of conflict deaths, (4) number of terrorism events, and (5) number of deaths from terrorism events. By contribution, it means how much a country has done to reduce armed violence and to improve global peace. This category is measured on the basis of two thematic indicators: (1) number of agreements and (2) achievements of agreements. Data on armed conflicts are collected and recoded from the UCDP Armed Conflict Dataset and UCDP Battle-related Deaths Dataset. Data on peace agreements are based on the UCDP Peace-agreement Dataset. Data on terrorism are from the Global Terror- ism Database (GTD). Because these data sources are widely used and respected, we adopt the concepts of “conflict” and “terrorism” defined in the datasets. Admittedly, 272 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 Table 6 Country ranking in the humanitarian aspect of promoting global justice Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 America 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 United Kingdom 2 2 2 2 2 2 3 3 Netherlands 7 6 6 8 7 5 6 8 Germany 5 3 3 4 3 4 2 2 Italy 12 14 18 16 11 12 11 7 Canada 6 5 4 5 5 6 5 5 Saudi Arabia 14 15 8 11 6 8 8 9 Kuwait 22 20 20 3 4 3 4 4 Spain 4 4 13 13 16 15 19 17 Ireland 16 16 15 14 15 16 15 15 France 9 9 10 15 8 10 7 6 Finland 15 13 12 10 10 13 13 14 Belgium 10 8 7 6 14 7 9 12 Afghanistan 36 85 82 68 89 75 82 73 Australia 8 10 11 9 12 14 14 13 Switzerland 13 11 9 7 9 9 12 10 Sweden 17 17 17 17 18 17 18 19 Norway 21 23 19 18 22 21 17 23 Denmark 23 25 24 19 20 19 20 21 New Zealand 32 24 27 26 27 26 26 24 Nepal 31 22 94 79 89 25 82 73 Greece 44 32 46 38 40 67 37 47 Luxembourg 27 29 22 21 24 23 23 26 United Arab Emirates 24 19 29 22 19 11 10 18 Turkey 11 12 23 24 25 28 29 22 Austria 26 28 26 23 28 24 21 20 Venezuela 105 36 94 79 17 84 82 73 China 20 18 21 29 23 22 24 16 Tajikistan 39 31 60 79 89 84 82 73 Azerbaijan 19 27 25 33 31 20 82 36 Thailand 47 72 84 60 55 35 73 53 Slovakia 49 105 43 41 60 45 33 35 Brazil 18 21 14 31 26 27 30 31 Romania 66 53 42 39 50 38 45 52 Estonia 42 37 35 28 32 30 25 27 Singapore 85 75 72 62 61 60 62 55 Poland 43 34 31 30 39 34 28 25 Japan 33 33 30 27 35 31 27 32 India 30 30 39 36 36 36 48 50 Belarus 34 40 33 32 42 33 32 38 Russian Federation 51 43 36 34 44 42 43 42 Bulgaria 62 55 41 37 56 43 38 39 273 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Table 6 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Portugal 45 57 45 40 38 39 47 51 Kenya 57 48 40 48 89 84 82 66 Slovenia 53 41 56 44 59 46 44 41 Malaysia 61 69 70 79 48 49 65 45 Lithuania 55 58 59 50 52 37 34 44 Kyrgyzstan 67 54 94 79 89 84 82 73 Latvia 81 52 54 45 47 48 57 73 Morocco 41 88 44 65 37 41 82 73 South Africa 68 50 47 49 49 51 54 46 Brunei Darussalam 99 73 63 79 53 84 82 73 Israel 98 78 69 79 43 84 82 73 Kazakhstan 59 56 76 61 64 54 61 64 Iraq 103 68 94 58 89 74 82 73 Czechia 73 62 50 43 57 44 48 49 Samoa 130 63 94 79 89 84 82 73 Monaco 79 67 64 54 63 55 58 73 Argentina 88 66 51 46 58 84 51 33 Malawi 130 105 37 79 89 40 82 73 Mozambique 112 105 52 69 89 84 82 73 Qatar 83 45 28 25 29 29 31 30 Malta 69 39 62 52 51 53 40 40 Tonga 130 60 94 79 89 84 82 73 Uzbekistan 89 71 94 79 89 84 82 73 Botswana 80 70 66 79 71 84 69 57 Philippines 97 44 34 35 45 71 60 29 Namibia 123 47 94 73 54 84 82 73 Ecuador 130 80 94 79 33 84 68 73 Cyprus 70 51 53 57 70 61 72 57 Sri Lanka 118 96 48 70 68 84 82 65 Andorra 72 65 65 53 65 63 66 59 Burkina Faso 102 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Peru 60 105 79 59 77 71 77 61 Mauritius 86 105 81 79 83 58 82 73 Ghana 25 105 61 79 89 84 82 73 Republic of Korea 105 82 73 63 69 65 67 60 Montenegro 91 42 68 55 66 84 75 73 Croatia 77 61 57 51 62 68 70 73 Tunisia 37 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Egypt 46 79 74 79 89 84 39 73 San Marino 92 76 77 79 78 76 82 68 Senegal 93 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Mexico 50 64 55 56 46 64 42 56 274 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 Table 6 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Guatemala 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Bosnia and Herzegovina 74 105 94 79 89 84 82 54 Hungary 110 90 78 64 75 69 64 63 Iceland 122 92 88 67 80 70 76 62 Pakistan 111 49 32 66 30 18 22 28 Nicaragua 130 94 94 79 89 84 82 73 Gabon 109 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Trinidad and Tobago 76 105 94 79 80 62 82 73 Cambodia 124 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Antigua and Barbuda 94 105 94 79 89 59 82 73 Bangladesh 56 87 75 79 89 50 79 34 United Republic of Tanzania 130 105 85 79 89 84 82 73 Algeria 52 38 94 42 83 84 59 66 Indonesia 116 95 86 71 83 84 82 73 Bhutan 125 97 90 79 89 52 82 69 Albania 130 100 82 79 89 84 82 73 Chile 126 97 91 75 82 76 80 69 Guyana 90 88 94 77 79 84 82 73 Laos 130 101 94 79 89 84 82 73 Mongolia 126 86 94 79 89 84 82 73 Viet Nam 126 101 94 79 89 84 82 73 Angola 130 46 94 79 89 84 82 73 Armenia 121 105 87 79 83 84 82 73 Bahamas 107 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Bahrain 29 105 94 20 21 56 82 73 Barbados 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Belize 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Benin 107 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Bolivia 130 105 94 79 34 84 82 73 Burundi 101 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Cameroon 130 105 94 79 89 73 82 73 Central African Republic 100 105 94 79 41 84 63 73 Chad 96 92 94 79 89 47 82 73 Colombia 95 105 91 72 87 80 82 73 Comoros 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Congo 87 74 94 79 89 84 82 73 Costa Rica 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Cuba 40 105 38 79 89 84 82 73 Côte d’Ivoire 130 101 71 79 89 80 82 69 Democratic Republic of the Congo 65 83 67 79 74 84 52 73 Dominica 130 105 94 79 89 84 56 73 Dominican Republic 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 275 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Table 6 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 El Salvador 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Equatorial Guinea 113 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Ethiopia 130 26 94 79 89 84 35 37 Fiji 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Gambia 63 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Georgia 64 59 94 47 67 57 50 73 Grenada 84 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Guinea 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Guinea-Bissau 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Haiti 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Honduras 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Iran 117 105 94 79 89 78 82 73 Jamaica 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Jordan 130 105 94 79 89 32 82 73 Lebanon 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Lesotho 130 105 94 79 89 84 36 73 Liberia 35 105 94 79 89 84 82 11 Libya 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Madagascar 114 105 94 79 89 84 41 73 Maldives 130 81 94 79 89 84 82 73 Mali 130 105 94 79 76 84 82 73 Marshall Islands 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Mauritania 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Micronesia 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Myanmar 126 91 91 77 88 80 80 69 Nauru 130 105 94 79 89 84 53 73 Niger 130 105 94 79 89 84 55 43 Nigeria 78 84 94 79 72 66 78 48 Oman 28 105 16 12 13 84 82 73 Palau 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Panama 103 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Papua New Guinea 130 105 94 79 89 84 46 73 Paraguay 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Republic of Moldova 71 77 80 79 89 84 82 73 Rwanda 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Sao Tome and Principe 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Serbia 114 101 94 75 89 80 71 73 Seychelles 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Sierra Leone 119 105 94 79 89 84 74 73 Solomon Islands 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Saint Kitts and Nevis 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Saint Lucia 75 97 94 79 89 84 82 73 276 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 the current methods of measurement and index construction in this issue area are imperfect; for example, several countries experienced sharp ups and downs in certain years, which call for a closer assessment of the methodological process. Based on the starting point of this project, we are open to insights and suggestions from all sides to further improve our ongoing research (Table 7). All the indicators are calculated in an accumulated count. For example, an observa- tion in the UCDP Armed Conflict Dataset indicates that there was a conflict between Table 6 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Saint Vincent and the Grenadines 82 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Sudan 3 7 94 79 89 84 82 73 Suriname 54 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Timor-Leste 38 35 94 79 89 84 82 73 Togo 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Turkmenistan 48 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Tuvalu 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Uganda 120 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Ukraine 58 105 58 79 89 84 82 73 Uruguay 130 105 88 73 72 79 82 73 Yemen 130 105 94 79 89 84 82 73 Zambia 130 105 49 79 89 84 82 73 Zimbabwe 130 105 5 79 89 84 16 73 Fig. 3 2017 index ranking of humanitarian aid on a world map 277 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Ta bl e 7 D at a on te rr or is m a nd a rm ed c on fli ct s C at eg or y D im en si on In di ca to r D at a so ur ce C ov er ag e Pe rf or m an ce Te rr or is m a nd c on fli ct s N um be r o f c on fli ct s U C D P A rm ed C on fli ct D at as et ; U C D P B at tle -r el at ed D ea th s D at as et 19 2 (2 01 0– 20 17 ) N um be r o f w ar s N um be r o f c on fli ct d ea th s N um be r o f t er ro ri sm e ve nt s N um be r o f d ea th s fr om te rr or is m e ve nt s C on tr ib ut io n C on fli ct a gr ee m en t N um be r o f a gr ee m en ts G T D A ch ie ve m en ts o f a gr ee m en ts 278 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 Afghanistan, Pakistan, and the United States in 2016 that reached the scale of the war (more than 1000 deaths). According to UCDP Battle-related Deaths Dataset, the esti- mate of the number of deaths caused by this conflict in 2016 was 2141. Thus, for these three countries, the number of conflicts and the number of wars all increased by 1 in 2016, and the total number of deaths involved in the conflict (number of conflict deaths) increased by 2141 in 2016. The indicator of agreements is measured according to the specific content of an agreement. More specifically, the UCDP Peace-agreement Dataset includes a series of variables that define the characteristics of an agreement (Table 8). Because countries with different population sizes experience different levels of governance challenges in managing conflicts and terrorism, the following indicators are weighted by population size in the corresponding year: (1) number of conflicts, (2) number of wars, (3) num- ber of conflict deaths, (4) number of terrorism events, and (5) number of deaths from terrorism events. The function to measure “achievements of agreements” is as follows: 3.5.2 Results Using index construction methods (see the methodological section), this sub-index ranks 192 countries from 2010 to 2017 according to their level of performance of and contribution to global justice (Table 9). The results demonstrate that the problems of conflicts, tensions, and terrorist threats remain alarming from 2010 to 2017, creating a substantial challenge to global jus- tice. According to the rank in 2017, China becomes the number one country and has the best performance best in controlling conflicts and terrorism and participating in peace agreements. China is followed by Japan, Brazil, Vietnam, the Republic of Korea, Uzbekistan, and Poland. Countries in Europe and North America are ranked Achievements of agreements = mil_prov + pol_prov + terr_prov + justice_prov + outlin + pko + (3 − pa_type)∕2. Table 8 Variable code Indicator Value Meaning mil_prov 0–1 Whether a military agreement is reached pol_prov 0–1 Whether a political agreement is reached terr_prov 0–1 Whether an agreement on the territory is reached justice_prov 0–1 Whether a judicial agreement is reached outlin 0–1 Whether a negotiation agenda is set pko 0–1 Whether the agreement specify peace keeping measures pa_type 1, 2, 3 Agreement quality: 1 = all, 2 = partial, 3 = preliminary 279 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Table 9 Country ranking in the terrorism and conflict aspect of promoting global justice Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 China 5 2 6 6 11 5 1 1 Japan 7 4 8 7 6 12 4 2 Brazil 6 3 7 9 5 6 2 3 Viet Nam 9 5 9 8 4 4 3 4 South Korea 29 28 29 24 29 8 6 5 Uzbekistan 17 12 12 12 10 14 7 6 Poland 42 35 37 28 37 7 13 7 Madagascar 26 27 26 27 19 23 23 8 North Korea 23 18 16 14 14 13 10 9 Argentina 33 10 17 15 9 10 8 10 Indonesia 8 21 30 21 17 15 9 11 Kazakhstan 28 78 62 49 16 18 49 12 Morocco 15 42 11 11 8 17 17 13 Guatemala 32 30 44 70 21 21 18 14 Cote d’Ivoire 27 23 19 20 15 24 14 15 Tanzania 14 8 10 30 36 45 12 16 Italy 54 36 48 33 39 16 26 17 Malawi 34 29 28 23 18 20 15 18 Romania 72 63 63 58 62 29 21 19 Mexico 13 6 33 26 7 25 5 20 Ghana 22 17 36 22 31 31 29 21 Cuba 39 38 39 29 30 32 27 22 Bolivia 46 45 55 31 32 35 28 23 Haiti 47 46 41 32 33 36 55 24 Spain 40 31 35 38 41 9 11 25 Cambodia 35 37 31 45 27 39 24 26 Malaysia 52 51 60 76 72 37 70 27 Zambia 38 32 32 25 22 22 19 28 Senegal 62 94 108 68 57 51 25 29 Belarus 75 85 72 35 35 40 32 30 Netherlands 82 77 69 65 94 86 83 31 Bangladesh 36 22 22 90 78 121 67 32 Ecuador 31 39 38 40 20 30 33 33 Angola 41 19 15 13 13 11 16 34 Germany 10 25 13 10 24 83 64 35 Guinea 45 43 40 62 38 65 42 36 America 20 9 14 16 23 34 38 37 Benin 51 50 46 43 42 48 34 38 Bulgaria 104 108 117 109 102 71 54 39 Zimbabwe 56 49 34 54 34 27 22 40 Dominican 49 48 43 46 44 38 30 41 Peru 16 13 58 60 56 56 31 42 280 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 Table 9 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Portugal 91 97 84 84 86 49 36 43 Nicaragua 74 65 64 55 80 52 43 44 Rwanda 108 72 101 94 54 44 40 45 Hungary 96 90 88 87 92 46 46 46 Kyrgyzstan 77 66 66 61 51 55 45 47 Canada 58 40 53 47 66 53 44 48 Honduras 57 68 49 73 48 41 47 49 Russian 127 112 106 102 55 50 68 50 Turkmenistan 79 71 67 64 76 58 50 51 Algeria 143 79 107 105 63 68 37 52 Singapore 119 116 115 111 53 59 51 53 Ethiopia 19 15 27 19 12 33 80 54 Iran 85 47 21 41 25 72 57 55 Slovakia 114 111 114 110 109 60 52 56 Uganda 99 16 54 18 85 54 86 57 Switzerland 61 81 52 67 40 61 56 58 Serbia 78 58 83 48 45 47 41 59 Congo 83 75 73 89 61 63 143 60 Costa Rica 80 73 71 66 59 64 59 61 Togo 64 60 61 63 52 66 48 62 Tajikistan 84 55 96 52 60 95 61 63 New Zealand 124 122 119 115 118 67 73 64 Lao 68 62 70 51 47 76 87 65 Oman 97 88 79 75 64 69 62 66 United Arab Emirates 105 96 91 97 116 100 100 67 Australia 66 59 59 53 90 93 72 68 South Africa 11 7 23 37 50 19 63 69 Croatia 125 123 121 123 117 70 65 70 Austria 102 100 95 99 97 57 69 71 Panama 88 82 76 74 65 75 78 72 El Salvador 70 107 109 107 104 73 58 73 Kuwait 98 101 82 78 67 127 113 74 Czechia 92 92 85 95 100 80 53 75 Mozambique 24 20 24 100 87 62 129 76 Azerbaijan 100 93 93 93 101 43 60 77 Venezuela 18 14 18 17 28 26 39 78 Eritrea 1 131 80 79 69 78 79 79 Denmark 121 110 112 112 128 119 114 80 Moldova 89 84 94 77 70 79 85 81 Chile 71 67 42 59 83 28 88 82 Uruguay 93 87 81 81 73 81 90 83 India 87 74 68 71 68 77 76 84 281 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Table 9 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 France 37 44 99 50 58 101 81 85 Tunisia 43 76 74 130 123 133 125 86 Mongolia 140 141 134 129 129 87 77 87 Georgia 152 143 135 127 127 91 109 88 Norway 123 157 116 114 114 84 66 89 Mauritania 109 115 78 86 77 92 75 90 Liberia 86 80 87 82 82 90 71 91 Namibia 107 102 103 101 89 97 89 92 Finland 115 113 113 113 111 115 91 93 Botswana 111 105 104 103 93 98 94 94 Papua New Guinea 63 57 56 44 43 42 35 95 Bosnia and Herzegovina 132 133 124 124 131 126 74 96 Albania 138 139 131 132 135 112 103 97 Lesotho 110 106 105 104 95 105 96 98 Sierra Leone 65 61 86 72 74 85 84 99 Slovenia 151 150 144 142 140 99 97 100 Belgium 90 86 89 85 110 96 119 101 Lithuania 135 137 130 126 130 88 92 102 Jamaica 101 95 90 91 91 89 82 103 Ukraine 48 41 57 39 2 3 104 104 Armenia 139 140 137 131 132 114 123 105 Republic of North Macedonia 150 148 150 141 146 123 95 106 Chad 55 34 47 57 71 156 93 107 Gambia 113 109 110 106 96 106 101 108 Trinidad and Tobago 136 124 120 138 106 118 112 109 Paraguay 94 99 97 120 121 132 124 110 Qatar 112 103 102 98 84 107 116 111 Sri Lanka 53 24 50 80 79 74 20 112 Mauritius 126 125 122 117 108 110 115 113 Equatorial Guinea 137 135 128 122 113 113 118 114 United Kingdom 103 89 92 118 105 104 106 115 Timor-Leste 130 128 123 119 112 111 117 116 Saudi Arabia 21 33 51 36 81 141 144 117 Cyprus 129 127 136 158 143 139 131 118 Sweden 106 98 98 96 103 131 110 119 Guinea-Bissau 122 117 125 116 107 116 111 120 Jordan 117 64 75 69 119 108 127 121 Eswatini 131 130 126 121 115 117 120 122 Burkina Faso 30 26 25 34 26 82 102 123 Latvia 148 149 145 143 142 109 99 124 Niger 76 54 45 88 75 162 133 125 Kenya 73 104 127 125 133 124 108 126 282 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 Table 9 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Thailand 153 145 147 155 145 134 142 127 Colombia 142 126 139 137 141 128 121 128 Turkey 67 91 138 92 99 147 163 129 Burundi 149 132 100 83 88 168 164 130 Fiji 141 142 133 128 122 122 126 131 Gabon 120 114 111 108 98 102 98 132 Sudan 4 134 1 3 151 142 145 133 Estonia 158 160 154 152 154 136 122 134 Myanmar 59 11 65 56 49 94 107 135 Comoros 146 147 142 134 126 129 128 136 Guyana 144 146 141 133 125 130 139 137 Democratic Republic of the Congo 95 69 4 4 120 125 132 138 Israel 128 161 159 145 174 150 153 139 Ireland 134 136 158 153 153 145 130 140 Greece 156 118 129 149 124 120 138 141 Solomon Islands 155 152 146 144 134 135 135 142 Montenegro 168 168 166 167 163 144 134 143 Lebanon 118 129 140 174 175 161 157 144 Luxembourg 172 172 169 166 164 137 136 145 Suriname 154 153 148 146 137 138 140 146 Egypt 12 53 77 140 136 157 147 147 Pakistan 159 163 164 165 160 155 148 148 Cabo Verde 157 155 149 148 139 140 141 149 Nigeria 81 119 151 147 162 163 151 150 Bhutan 147 154 143 135 138 143 137 151 Brunei 161 158 155 151 144 146 152 152 Cameroon 60 52 20 42 157 166 146 153 Djibouti 2 144 153 139 150 151 149 154 Bahamas 163 162 156 157 148 148 155 155 Belize 164 164 157 160 149 149 156 156 Philippines 133 121 132 154 147 152 154 157 Iceland 180 179 179 173 176 153 159 158 Nepal 116 120 118 136 46 103 105 159 Barbados 166 165 161 156 155 158 161 160 Vanuatu 167 167 163 159 156 159 162 161 Maldives 162 159 160 161 169 160 158 162 Malta 160 156 152 150 152 154 150 163 Mali 44 70 3 2 3 2 160 164 Sao Tome and Principe 170 170 167 162 158 164 166 165 Samoa 169 169 165 163 159 165 167 166 Saint Lucia 171 171 168 164 161 167 168 167 Yemen 165 166 171 168 178 181 178 168 283 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 in the middle, for example, Germany is ranked 35th and the United States is ranked 37th. The reason for these two rankings is mainly because European countries and the United States have participated in international peace affairs, but have been involved in international and regional conflicts. Tuvalu and Nauru remain the two countries with the least impact on global justice in the issue area of terrorism and armed conflicts, a position it has held since 2014. Other countries on the bottom include Syria, Somalia, Afghanistan, Iraq, Palau, and Nauru. Although the ranks fluctuated during the obser- vation period, we observe that the 10-year trend is relatively stable and reflects the general situation on the ground. Figure 4, a world map of the 2017 index ranking, reveals that countries in the Mid- dle East and North Africa (the MENA region), Central Africa, and South Asia must do more to decrease conflicts and terrorist threats. Most countries in East Asia and South- east Asia contribute to global justice in a sense that they made progress in govern- ing conflicts and terrorism (except for the Philippines). Many countries in Europe and North America have room to improve in managing terrorism and reducing involve- ment in global or regional conflicts. Table 9 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Bahrain 145 138 176 181 177 170 165 169 South Sudan 50 56 2 1 1 1 170 170 Kiribati 178 177 174 171 165 171 171 171 Micronesia 179 178 175 172 168 174 173 172 Grenada 175 176 173 170 166 172 172 173 Saint Vincent and the Grenadines 174 175 172 169 167 173 174 174 Tonga 177 189 189 188 187 175 175 175 Seychelles 181 181 178 176 171 177 176 176 Antigua and Barbuda 182 180 177 175 170 176 177 177 Andorra 183 182 180 177 172 178 179 178 Dominica 184 183 181 179 173 179 180 179 Libya 69 83 162 184 189 188 188 180 Marshall Islands 185 184 183 182 179 180 181 181 Central African 3 1 5 5 182 169 169 182 Syrian 25 151 170 178 181 186 185 183 Saint Kitts and Nevis 186 185 184 183 180 182 182 184 Monaco 188 187 186 185 183 184 183 185 Somalia 173 173 182 180 186 183 184 186 San Marino 189 188 188 187 184 185 186 187 Afghanistan 176 174 187 186 185 187 187 188 Iraq 187 186 185 189 191 189 190 189 Palau 190 190 190 190 188 190 189 190 Nauru 192 192 192 192 190 191 191 191 Tuvalu 191 191 191 191 192 192 192 192 284 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 3.6 Issue 5: Cross‑National Criminal Police Cooperation Transnational crimes are crimes that involve more than one country in their plan- ning and organization and are always accompanied by effects across national borders. Transnational crimes, because of their suggested cross-national harm on citizens, pose serious challenges to global justice. As a result, fighting transnational crimes has been a major domain of global cooperation to improve global justice. We involved this issue into our global justice index and measure each country’s contributions to fighting transnational crimes, by evaluating their financial contribution to Interpol and their promises to the relevant UN conventions. 3.6.1 Dimensions and Indicators We used two major categories to measure transnational criminal cooperation, and each comprises several indicators. The first category is the financial contribution to Interpol (the International Criminal Police Organization). Because transnational crime involves more than one country, an international organization with a well-established commu- nication system is necessary to connect all of the countries, which is what Interpol does. Interpol is the biggest organization worldwide that provides technical and opera- tional supports to combat transnational crime.2 Financial donations to Interpol reflect the determination and contribution of a country to cross-national criminal coopera- tion. Thus, in addition, we measure the ratification status of each country to the UN Fig. 4 2017 index ranking of conflicts and terrorism on a world map 2 Please check https ://www.inter pol.int/en for more information about Interpol. https://www.interpol.int/en 285 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 treaties in regards to transnational crime cooperation. These treaties include the United Nations Convention against Transnational Organized Crime and its three supplement- ing protocols.3 Ratification of the treaties denotes compliance with the related require- ments and the promise to offer relevant assistance. As a result, the ratification status of each country also shows their contribution to the cross-national criminal cooperation (Table 10). Data for the past 8 years show that the US has always been the highest contributor. Traditional liberal democracies, such as Germany, Italy, France, Britain, the Nether- lands, Canada, Spain, and Belgium, have almost dominated the top ten lists. Countries in Latin America with serious problems of transnational crimes, such as Brazil and Mexico, have made substantial contributions to combat transnational crime and are within the top 15 contributors. China is the top contributor in Asia and ranks 10th in 2007. Additionally, China has been one of the top 20 contributors for the past 8 years. Increases in ranking are observed in Japan in 2017 and in the Republic of Korea in 2015, which is after they began to ratify the UN treaties that they had not signed (Table 11). The map shows each county’s contribution in 2017. The darker color denotes a higher rank. We observe that countries in North America, South America, Europe, and Australia made relatively greater contributions compared with nations in Africa and Southeast Asia. In Africa, Algeria, Libya, and South Africa contributed relatively more than did the other countries (Fig. 5). 3.7 Issue 6: Anti‑poverty The problem of global poverty constitutes a substantial challenge to maintaining global justice. A widespread concern is that the world becomes increasingly unjust when economic growth is not equitably distributed, and in the past decade, the gap widened between the rich and poor. According to estimates from the Work Bank, at least 10% of the world’s population lives on less than US$1.90 a day. Poverty allevia- tion is of substantial importance to improving global justice. Although global poverty rates have been largely decreased over the past decades, the performance of reducing poverty has been uneven in different regions and countries. Hence, this anti-poverty index helps to evaluate individual countries’ efforts and performance in poverty reduc- tion, as a means to improve global justice. 3.7.1 Dimensions and Indicators Based on the goods-based conception of global justice and the principle of CDDR (as elaborated in our concept paper), we assume that efforts to combat global poverty 3 These three protocols include the Protocol to Prevent, Suppress and Punish Trafficking in Persons, especially Women and Children; Protocol against the Smuggling of Migrants by Land, Sea and Air; and Protocol against the Illicit Manufacturing of and Trafficking in Firearms, their Parts and Components and Ammunition. 286 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 Ta bl e 10 D at a on c ro ss -n at io na l c ri m in al p ol ic e co op er at io n Is su e ar ea C at eg or y In di ca to r So ur ce C ov er ag e C ro ss -n at io na l C ri m in al P ol ic e C oo pe ra tio n Pe rf or m an ce (t re at y ra tifi - ca tio n) U ni te d N at io ns C on ve nt io n ag ai ns t T ra ns na tio na l O rg an - iz ed C ri m e (2 00 0) U ni te d N at io ns O ffi ce on D ru gs a nd C ri m e (U N O D C ) 18 4 (2 01 0– 20 17 ) Pr ot oc ol to P re ve nt , S up pr es s an d Pu ni sh T ra ffi ck in g in Pe rs on s, E sp ec ia lly W om en a nd C hi ld re n, s up pl em en t- in g th e U ni te d N at io ns C on ve nt io n ag ai ns t T ra ns na tio na l O rg an iz ed C ri m e (2 00 3) Pr ot oc ol a ga in st th e Sm ug gl in g of M ig ra nt s by L an d, S ea an d A ir, s up pl em en tin g th e U ni te d N at io ns C on ve nt io n ag ai ns t T ra ns na tio na l O rg an iz ed C ri m e (2 00 4) Pr ot oc ol a ga in st th e Il lic it M an uf ac tu ri ng o f a nd T ra f- fic ki ng in F ir ea rm s, T he ir P ar ts a nd C om po ne nt s an d A m m un iti on , s up pl em en tin g th e U ni te d N at io ns C on - ve nt io n ag ai ns t T ra ns na tio na l O rg an iz ed C ri m e (2 00 5) C on tr ib ut io n D on at io n to In te rp ol In te rp ol 287 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Table 11 Country ranking in the cross-national criminal police cooperation Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 United States of America 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 Germany 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 3 Italy 3 3 3 3 3 3 3 5 France 4 4 4 4 4 4 4 4 United Kingdom 5 5 5 5 5 5 5 6 Netherlands 6 6 7 8 8 8 8 11 Canada 7 8 8 7 7 7 7 8 Spain 8 6 6 6 6 6 6 7 Belgium 9 10 11 11 11 13 15 16 Switzerland 10 11 9 9 9 10 12 14 Sweden 11 9 10 10 10 11 14 15 Australia 12 12 12 14 14 16 16 17 Brazil 13 13 14 15 15 14 10 9 Austria 14 15 17 12 13 15 17 18 Mexico 15 14 13 13 12 12 11 13 Norway 16 16 15 16 16 18 18 21 Denmark 17 17 16 17 17 19 20 24 Poland 18 20 20 20 20 20 19 22 China 19 19 18 18 18 17 13 10 Argentina 20 21 22 23 23 26 26 28 Saudi Arabia 21 23 21 21 21 21 22 23 Turkey 22 24 24 24 25 24 21 20 Russian Federation 23 26 27 27 28 25 23 19 Finland 24 18 19 19 19 22 24 25 Slovakia 25 28 28 29 31 33 34 36 South Africa 26 29 29 28 29 30 31 32 Chile 27 31 31 31 32 34 33 34 Kuwait 28 32 32 33 34 35 35 35 Libya 29 33 33 34 35 36 37 38 Peru 30 34 34 36 37 39 39 40 Slovenia 31 35 35 35 36 38 40 41 Algeria 32 36 36 37 38 39 38 39 Oman 33 37 37 38 39 41 41 42 Romania 34 38 38 39 40 37 36 37 Uruguay 35 39 39 45 46 48 49 50 Croatia 36 40 40 41 42 42 42 43 Nigeria 36 41 40 42 43 44 45 46 Cyprus 38 42 42 44 45 47 48 51 Dominican Republic 39 43 43 46 47 50 52 53 Kazakhstan 40 44 44 47 48 46 43 44 Lithuania 40 44 44 47 48 62 47 48 Belarus 40 44 44 47 48 50 51 52 288 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 Table 11 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Bulgaria 40 44 44 47 48 52 52 53 Latvia 40 44 44 47 48 52 52 53 Trinidad and Tobago 40 44 44 47 48 54 55 56 Lebanon 40 44 44 47 48 54 55 58 Serbia 40 44 44 47 48 54 55 59 Estonia 40 44 44 47 48 54 55 59 Azerbaijan 40 44 44 47 48 54 55 59 Costa Rica 40 44 44 47 48 60 61 62 Tunisia 40 44 44 47 48 60 61 63 Honduras 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Zambia 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Montenegro 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Mongolia 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Nicaragua 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Laos 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Burkina Faso 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Saint Vincent and the Grenadines 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Republic of Moldova 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Senegal 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Paraguay 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Kenya 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Guyana 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Panama 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Cambodia 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Liberia 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Madagascar 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Rwanda 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Mali 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Jamaica 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Mauritius 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 El Salvador 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Guatemala 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Central African Republic 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Albania 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Sao Tome and Principe 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Malawi 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Turkmenistan 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Antigua and Barbuda 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Bahamas 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Mauritania 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Saint Kitts and Nevis 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Benin 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 289 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Table 11 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Democratic Republic of the Congo 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Bosnia and Herzegovina 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 United Republic of Tanzania 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Mozambique 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Lesotho 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Grenada 40 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Portugal 91 25 25 25 26 28 28 29 New Zealand 92 96 101 108 112 113 113 116 Hungary 93 30 30 30 30 31 32 33 Venezuela 94 97 103 32 33 32 30 31 Indonesia 95 98 104 110 114 114 114 117 Egypt 96 99 105 111 115 116 116 119 Philippines 97 100 106 112 116 117 117 119 Ukraine 98 102 108 42 44 43 43 45 Iraq 99 103 109 47 48 49 49 49 Ecuador 99 103 109 47 48 54 55 56 Togo 99 103 44 47 48 62 63 64 Armenia 99 103 44 47 48 62 63 64 Bahrain 99 103 109 114 118 119 119 122 Niger 99 103 109 114 118 120 120 123 Gambia 99 103 109 114 118 120 120 123 Namibia 99 103 109 114 118 120 120 123 Tajikistan 99 103 109 114 118 120 120 123 Cameroon 99 103 109 114 118 120 120 123 Gabon 99 103 109 114 118 120 120 123 Botswana 99 103 109 114 118 120 120 123 Malta 99 103 109 114 118 120 120 123 Georgia 99 103 109 114 118 120 120 123 Timor-Leste 99 103 109 114 118 120 120 123 Belize 99 103 109 114 118 120 120 123 Djibouti 99 103 109 114 118 120 120 123 Kyrgyzstan 99 103 109 114 118 120 120 123 Monaco 99 103 109 114 118 120 120 123 Myanmar 99 103 109 114 118 120 120 123 San Marino 99 103 109 114 118 120 120 123 Guinea 99 103 109 114 118 120 120 123 Suriname 99 103 109 114 118 120 120 123 Seychelles 99 103 109 114 118 120 120 123 Ireland 123 127 133 137 140 141 141 144 Israel 124 128 134 138 141 142 142 146 Luxembourg 125 130 102 109 113 115 115 118 United Arab Emirates 126 129 135 139 142 144 143 145 290 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 Table 11 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Malaysia 127 131 136 141 144 145 145 148 Iceland 128 133 138 143 146 149 149 152 Colombia 129 132 137 142 145 147 147 150 Qatar 130 134 139 144 147 148 148 151 Morocco 131 101 107 113 117 118 118 121 Cuba 132 135 140 40 41 45 46 47 Guinea-Bissau 133 136 141 114 118 120 120 123 Uzbekistan 133 136 141 145 148 151 151 154 Equatorial Guinea 133 136 141 145 148 151 151 154 Jordan 133 136 141 145 148 151 151 154 Bolivia 133 136 141 145 148 151 151 154 Uganda 133 136 141 145 148 151 151 154 Chad 133 136 141 145 148 151 151 154 Japan 140 145 151 156 162 176 176 2 Singapore 141 144 150 155 161 143 144 147 Pakistan 142 146 152 157 163 164 165 167 Ethiopia 143 147 44 47 48 62 63 64 Afghanistan 143 147 153 158 148 151 151 123 Zimbabwe 143 147 153 145 148 151 151 154 Sudan 143 147 153 158 148 151 151 154 Sri Lanka 143 147 153 158 164 151 151 154 Comoros 143 147 153 158 164 166 166 168 Congo 143 147 153 158 164 166 166 168 Brunei Darussalam 143 147 153 158 164 166 166 168 Yemen 143 147 153 158 164 166 166 168 Micronesia 152 143 149 154 160 163 164 166 Republic of Korea 153 160 165 171 176 9 9 12 Czechia 154 161 166 107 24 27 29 30 Greece 155 22 23 22 22 23 25 26 India 156 27 26 26 27 29 27 27 Thailand 157 162 167 140 143 146 146 149 Iran (Islamic Republic of) 158 163 168 172 177 177 177 178 Haiti 159 44 44 47 48 62 63 64 Burundi 159 164 44 47 48 62 63 64 Nauru 159 164 44 47 48 62 63 64 Dominica 159 164 169 47 48 62 63 64 Ghana 159 164 109 114 48 62 63 64 Angola 159 164 169 158 48 62 63 64 Barbados 159 164 169 173 48 62 63 64 Sierra Leone 159 164 169 173 48 62 63 64 Côte d’Ivoire 159 164 109 114 118 120 120 64 Fiji 159 164 169 173 178 178 178 64 291 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 should respect the action of individual countries involved in improving the living conditions for the least advantaged within their respective jurisdictions. Therefore, to assess the contributions made by each country to global poverty eradication, we Table 11 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Viet Nam 159 164 141 145 148 150 150 153 Saint Lucia 159 164 169 145 148 151 151 154 Eritrea 159 164 169 173 148 151 151 154 Maldives 159 164 169 158 164 165 151 154 Marshall Islands 159 147 153 158 164 166 166 168 Bangladesh 159 147 153 158 164 166 166 168 Andorra 159 147 153 158 164 166 166 168 Nepal 159 147 153 158 164 166 166 168 Tonga 159 164 169 173 164 166 166 168 Bhutan 159 164 169 173 178 178 178 179 Papua New Guinea 159 164 169 173 178 178 178 179 Samoa 180 164 169 173 164 166 166 168 South Sudan 180 181 169 173 178 178 178 179 Solomon Islands 180 181 182 182 182 182 182 182 Palau 180 181 182 182 182 182 182 182 Tuvalu 180 181 182 182 182 182 182 182 Fig. 5 2017 index ranking of cross-national criminal police cooperation on a world map 292 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 measure their progress in poverty reduction by focusing on three thematic indictors: (1) Gini index, (2) poverty gap, and (3) poverty rate.4 The World Bank is the main source of global information on extreme poverty. However, the global poverty data provided by the World Bank are primarily for devel- oping countries. Moreover, the data of developing countries suffer severe problems of missing values, with data appearing in certain years and missing in other years. Later in this report, we explain the imputation methods which we used to compensate for missing data of this type. To include more observation cases of developed countries, we supplement the World Bank poverty data with related information from the OECD Income Distribution Database. However, substantial challenges remain, because the two datasets use different statistical benchmarks and scales to measure the three indi- cators we use. To make the data comparable, we calculate the ranking score by meas- uring the extent to which the country’s performance in reducing poverty in a given year has improved compared with the year before. The data sources available limited our ability to rank all nation states (Table 12). 3.7.2 Results Due to data limitations, this sub-index currently has ranked 60–82 countries over the period of 2010–2017 (Table 13). The results reveal that except for the countries with missing data, the largest improvements in poverty relief were in developing countries, for example, Thailand and Argentina. There are a few clear patterns in the data. No country managed to improve on all three indicator domains—Gini index, poverty gap, and poverty rate. Moreover, the progress made by individual countries is unstable. Because this sub- index is calculated by measuring the improvement in poverty reduction performance compared with the last observation year, we easily understand that there are very rare cases that can make continuous rapid progress over 1 decade (Fig. 6). A world map of the 2017 index ranking of poverty relief demonstrates that coun- tries in Latin America made significant progress in addressing poverty problems com- pared with their performance in 2016. The countries of the Organisation for Economic Table 12 Data on anti-poverty Category Indicator Data source Coverage Performance Gini Index World Bank; OECD Income Distribution Database 60–82 (2010–2017) Poverty gap Poverty rate 4 Individual countries’ international commitment to reduce global poverty in other poor countries and regions is assessed by “humanitarian aid” in our project. Notably, many other aspects and indicators can be used to measure global poverty (e.g., living conditions). We excluded them from our measurement because of the severe problems in data quality and richness. We also provide statistical evidence that the omission of these indictors does not significantly affect the assessment and ranking. 293 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Table 13 Country ranking in anti-poverty aspect of promoting global justice Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Ukraine 2 15 18 5 48 64 3 1 Kazakhstan 6 2 5 4 53 58 60 2 Argentina 5 6 32 33 47 7 56 3 Republic of Moldova 7 4 17 6 3 37 19 4 Uruguay 8 7 31 70 5 36 4 5 Paraguay 22 33 4 11 56 17 43 6 Romania 60 81 74 76 29 13 18 7 El Salvador 20 42 12 13 40 12 39 8 Dominican Republic 19 51 49 27 11 9 5 9 Thailand 9 2 55 2 17 2 59 10 Armenia 46 54 8 69 26 15 17 11 Cyprus 2 NA NA NA 34 1 NA 12 Bolivia (Plurinational State of) 34 10 68 19 20 41 53 13 Estonia 63 78 9 77 7 4 32 14 Ecuador 11 16 24 17 9 57 28 15 Indonesia 13 21 19 21 14 16 8 16 Colombia 14 19 34 26 16 19 30 17 Lithuania 16 63 72 47 61 56 52 18 Spain 43 69 47 80 33 45 25 19 Luxembourg 32 65 71 66 57 53 48 20 Mexico 10 31 51 63 63 10 58 21 Hungary 52 72 77 30 58 44 20 22 Canada 36 75 36 48 45 30 26 23 Republic of Korea 18 59 70 37 59 55 37 24 Switzerland 49 56 29 34 60 20 51 25 Ireland 55 35 53 18 64 18 50 26 Israel 53 34 61 60 36 46 12 27 Brazil 23 60 35 56 15 59 6 28 Denmark 26 66 42 68 31 31 42 29 Latvia 15 73 66 59 54 34 41 30 Czechia 33 49 22 74 46 49 27 31 Austria 28 67 60 29 27 52 44 32 Costa Rica 31 37 23 72 28 48 7 33 Belgium 38 61 62 44 22 51 23 34 Germany 27 39 25 67 51 50 45 35 Italy 57 41 58 58 38 54 11 36 Greece 59 79 67 38 52 29 9 37 Portugal 24 74 75 61 24 24 24 38 Panama 54 11 76 15 55 6 29 39 Sweden 51 48 16 75 21 32 46 40 United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland 44 62 56 51 41 38 35 41 Serbia 65 5 79 78 10 5 61 42 294 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 Co-operation and Development (OECD) in North America and Europe show very slight improvements in reducing poverty, because these countries have largely elimi- nated extreme poverty and suffer from ceiling effects. Russia has much more room for improvement in its anti-poverty efforts. Due to data limitations (especially the missing data), we could not obtain a reliable ranking for many countries in Asia and Africa. However, it is worth noting that China’s poverty alleviation campaign in recent years has borne outstanding results. However, as data sources differ in statistical criteria, the results were not duly represented on the index, which greatly undermined its rankings. Our poverty index is based on three key indicators: Gini coefficient, poverty gap, and poverty rate. Unfortunately, because of differences in statistical methods and criteria, we have not found well-testified data related to China to replace or complement World Bank’s data for the indicators mentioned above. 1. Gini coefficient Gini coefficient is a widely used indicator for measuring the income disparity in a country or region. “Gini coefficient is calculated with income data by household Table 13 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Netherlands 35 58 64 62 44 40 40 43 Montenegro 25 82 81 35 3 62 54 44 Slovakia 47 64 57 65 30 27 36 45 Peru 12 25 15 25 18 22 16 46 Slovenia 50 68 21 71 32 43 15 47 Kyrgyzstan 62 14 80 73 4 61 2 48 Iceland 39 29 54 31 62 21 21 49 United States of America 45 55 59 57 37 25 49 50 Norway 40 70 63 50 43 35 34 51 Turkey 37 23 41 36 25 33 31 52 Finland 48 50 52 53 39 26 22 53 France 41 44 65 40 42 42 33 54 Russian Federation 30 8 48 10 49 23 55 55 Georgia 58 30 6 12 8 11 38 56 Poland 29 57 73 64 35 28 13 57 Honduras 56 80 78 24 19 39 14 58 Belarus 4 18 2 3 6 63 10 59 Malta 3 71 14 2 3 NA 1 60 Iran (Islamic Republic of) NA NA NA NA 66 60 47 NA Croatia 61 17 69 54 50 8 NA NA China NA 46 45 14 23 14 NA NA Republic of North Macedonia 42 27 13 16 12 47 NA NA Bulgaria 64 77 33 42 13 NA NA NA Djibouti NA NA NA 79 NA NA NA NA Mongolia NA 9 3 NA NA NA NA NA New Zealand NA NA 39 NA NA NA NA NA Pakistan NA 40 NA NA NA NA NA NA 295 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 or group. It varies with the source and criteria of the basic income data used. For instance, whether the income standards are testified, whether the general income standards or the disposable income standards should be used, whether the income data include in-kind benefits from government, or whether annual CPIs or regional price differences are taken into account, all these have an effect on the coefficient and its changes. One must pay attention to the comparability of basic data when making inter- national or temporal comparisons of Gini coefficients.”5 The Chinese National Bureau of Statistics has released China’s Gini coefficients from 2003 to 2016, which range from 0.45 to 0.5. They were calculated based on data from a sample survey of urban and rural household income and expenditure around the country,6 whereas the Gini coefficients released by the World Bank were calcu- lated based on data from surveys carried out by national governments and estimates Fig. 6 2017 index ranking of poverty reduction on a world map 5 WANG, Pingping. A Few Issues Regarding the Calculation of Gini Coefficients on China’s Resident Income. (http://www.stats .gov.cn/ztjc/ztfx/grdd/20130 2/t2013 0201_59099 .html). 6 As of December 2012, the national survey of urban and rural household income and expenditure had a sample size of 140,000 households—74,000 rural from 896 countries, randomly sampled through a strat- ified and multi-phase process, and 66,000 urban from 476 cities and counties, randomly sampled through a stratified and two-phase process. At the end of 2012, the National Bureau of Statistics established a new and unified household survey system and a uniform income index system, and selected a consistent survey sample. Since December 1, 2012, the 400,000 sampled households across the country have been surveyed pursuant to the new survey system. Please see WANG, Pingping: A Few Issues Regarding the Calculation of Gini Coefficients on China’s Resident Income. http://www.stats.gov.cn/ztjc/ztfx/grdd/201302/t20130201_59099.html 296 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 made by agencies under the World Bank.7 The two adopt different statistical methods and samples. From the above line chart, we can see that China’s Gini coefficients calculated by the National Bureau of Statistics are even higher than those of the World Bank. There- fore, they cannot be directly used to replace the latter’s statistics. To ensure that the poverty data are comparable across countries, we chose to use the Gini coefficients calculated by the World Bank. 2. Poverty gap Apart from the Gini coefficients, a lot of data on China’s poverty gap in recent years are also missing. Available data are particularly lacking in the calculation of each country’s poverty alleviation index. Poverty gap refers to the average income shortfall in proportion to the poverty line of poor families,8 and it is used to measure the depth of poverty in a country. The uni- versally accepted criteria are the following: poverty gap at $1.90 a day (2011 PPP) (% population); poverty gap at $3.20 a day (2011 PPP) (% of population); and poverty gap at $5.50 a day (2011 PPP) (% of population). It means that different poverty lines (e.g., US$1.9 per day, US$3.2 per day, US$5.5 per day, etc.) are defined on the basis of the international purchasing power parity (PPP) of 2011 to measure the size of impover- ished population and poverty gap.9 Chinese authorities adopt the average disposable income of urban residents, rural residents, and others as criteria. So far, we have not found any shared criterion between them and the World Bank. According to the Working Plan for Archiving Pov- erty Alleviation and Development Records published by the State Council’s Leading 9 Purchasing Power Parity (PPP), as a currency converter, is used as a solution to the issue of currency differences in cross-national comparisons, corrected for differences in price level. PPP estimates cur- rently used by the World Bank are based on the 2011 round of International Comparison Program, which is by far the most extensive international statistical survey involving the largest number of countries. 7 See: https ://datab ank.world bank.org/metad atagl ossar y/gende r-stati stics /serie s/SI.POV.GINI. 8 Please see: “Millennium Development Goal Indicators.” United Nations. 2008. https://databank.worldbank.org/metadataglossary/gender-statistics/series/SI.POV.GINI 297 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Group Office of Poverty Alleviation and Development in April 2014, during China’s “targeted poverty alleviation” campaign, “the national rural poverty line—RMB 2736 yuan, the per capita net income of rural residents in 2013 (2300 yuan in constant prices in 2010)—shall be adopted as the identification standard for the impoverished population.”10 The standard is adjusted every year in accordance with variations in CPI, cost-of-living index, etc., and it is much different from the statistical methods and criteria used by the World Bank and relevant UN organizations.11 For this reason, it is not suitable for direct cross-national comparisons, and is thus not included in the calculation of our index. 3. Poverty rate We faced the same issue in the poverty rate calculation. World Bank’s poverty headcount ratios are calculated based on the poverty lines determined on the basis of the PPP in 2011 (e.g., US$1.9 per day, US$3.2 per day, US$5.5 per day, etc.): poverty headcount ratio at $1.90 a day (2011 PPP) (% of population); poverty headcount ratio at $3.20 a day (2011 PPP) (% of population); poverty headcount ratio at $5.50 a day (2011 PPP) (% of population). In its targeted poverty alleviation campaign, the Chinese government adopted “pov- erty incidence” as a major evaluation criterion. [Poverty incidence = number of indi- viduals in poverty ÷ total headcount × 100%]. This rate is based on the poverty line of RMB 2300 yuan (per capita net income), which makes it rather different from World Bank’s statistical methods and criteria, and not suitable as a direct alternative to them. To ensure a plausible and operable comparative analysis of poverty data across dif- ferent countries, including that on China, we chose one single data source—the World Bank. The downside of this choice is that not all the data of every country in every year are represented by the resulting rankings, as many years’ numbers are missing and the data of recent years are not updated in a timely manner. We believe that the issue will be resolved when new data are released in succession, and we keep improv- ing our calculation methods. There is no doubt that “targeted poverty alleviation” and China’s other agendas for enhancing global justice have borne remarkable results. In the future, our project will be dedicated to the collection of country-specific data and exploration of conversion methods of different poverty lines to improve the compara- bility of China’s poverty alleviation data with its international counterparts and extend the coverage of the Global Justice-Anti-poverty Index to more countries and years. 3.8 Issue 7: Education Education is essential for global justice. The  Convention on the Rights of the Child and the  International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights  explicitly 10 At the Central Working Conference on Poverty Alleviation and Development in Beijing on November 29, 2011, Wen Jiabao, then Premier of the State Council, announced that the central government would adopt the average net income of rural residents—RMB 2300 yuan—as the new national poverty relief standard. 11 Many research institutes and media agencies believe that the poverty line currently adopted by China is higher than that of the World Bank. 298 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 highlight states’ obligations to take measures toward realizing the right to education, to which the principle of CDDR applies (as elaborated in our concept paper). There is an international consensus as to the protection of rights to education. To improve global justice, steps must be taken by nation states to realize the basic human right of receiving education, using the maximum available resources. 3.8.1 Dimensions and Indicators Based on internationally recognized components of the right to education, this pro- ject measures each country’s influence on global justice in education by focusing on two categories: performance and contribution. We first focus on individual countries’ performance on basic education, by measuring the extent to which an individual’s educational right is adequately protected. Drawing on the literature, this category is measured along three thematic indicators: (1) school enrollment ratio, (2) children out of school, (3) pupil–teacher ratio. For the category of contribution, we assess the gov- ernment’s effort to improve its basic education nationwide by measuring government expenditure on education per capital while determining if a state is fulfilling its basic obligation.  The World Bank is the main source of global information on education (Table 14). 3.8.2 Results Using index construction methods (see the methodological section), this sub-index ranks 76–105 countries from 2010 to 2017 (Table 15). The data indicate that most countries take the necessary measures to protect chil- dren’s educational rights. The OECD countries including Sweden, Finland, the United Kingdom, Germany, France, and Ireland do particularly well in this domain. East Asian countries emphasis on education has been well documented, China and the Republic of Korea score relatively strongly in this issue area. Some rich countries in the Middle East and the Gulf Region such as Qatar and Israel have also invested heavily in education. Except for the countries with missing data, developing countries, including Pakistan, Tanzania, Niger, Mali, Guinea, and Senegal, are at the bottom. This finding largely occurs, because these countries either have insufficient educa- tional resources or are experiencing political instability. Although the country ranking fluctuates slightly, the general pattern is stable over the observation decade. On a world map (Fig. 7), the 2017 index ranking of countries in the domain of edu- cation illustrates that the Nordic countries including Sweden and Finland maintain their good score and are closely followed by other Western European countries such as the United Kingdom, Germany, and France. Notably, Eastern European countries, namely, Cyprus, Slovenia, Poland, and Hungary are also doing well compared with many other countries and regions in the world. Some disparities exist in the implementation of the right to education in Latin America, with Argentina ranked 18th and Uruguay at 46th. Countries in Western Africa and South Asia are in a concerning situation of fulfilling the mandates that the state actively create the conditions necessary for individuals’ enjoyment 299 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Ta bl e 14 D at a on e du ca tio n C at eg or y D im en si on In di ca to r D at a so ur ce C ov er ag e Pe rf or m an ce E nr ol lm en t r at io Sc ho ol e nr ol lm en t r at io , p ri m ar y (% n et ) W or ld B an k 76 –1 05 (2 01 0– 20 17 ) C om pl et io n ra te s C hi ld re n ou t o f s ch oo l ( % o f p ri m ar y sc ho ol a ge ) Te ac he rs Pu pi l– te ac he r r at io , p ri m ar y C on tr ib ut io n G ov er nm en t e xp en di tu re o n ed uc at io n G ov er nm en t e xp en di tu re o n ed uc at io n pe r c ap ita l 300 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 Table 15 Country ranking in education aspect of promoting global justice Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Sweden 1 2 1 2 5 4 4 1 Finland 3 4 6 5 8 5 5 2 China 4 1 3 7 4 6 3 3 New Zealand NA NA NA 9 13 10 6 4 United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland 7 10 10 12 12 8 7 5 Israel 10 13 14 15 17 14 10 6 Germany 8 9 11 13 15 12 8 7 France 6 8 12 14 16 13 9 8 Ireland 5 6 9 11 14 11 12 9 Qatar 2 5 8 6 11 9 11 10 Cyprus 9 11 13 17 19 16 16 11 Republic of Korea 16 18 19 20 22 15 17 12 Spain 12 16 16 21 23 19 19 13 Slovenia 14 17 20 22 25 20 21 14 Portugal 15 19 22 23 26 21 22 15 Oman NA NA NA NA NA NA NA 16 Estonia 19 22 26 25 27 23 24 17 Argentina 25 25 28 28 32 24 26 18 Latvia 27 30 24 24 30 26 29 19 Chile 28 35 33 33 38 28 30 20 Cuba 20 23 23 35 40 30 31 21 Barbados 17 21 25 27 29 22 27 22 Brazil 18 20 21 26 28 27 28 23 Poland 21 26 29 30 31 29 32 24 Hungary 23 31 35 40 39 33 34 25 Lithuania 22 27 31 31 33 31 33 26 Russian Federation 29 24 27 29 35 37 39 27 Bahrain NA 36 34 38 41 32 35 28 Malaysia 30 29 30 34 37 35 36 29 Mauritius 39 44 45 46 44 39 40 30 Croatia 26 33 38 37 43 38 41 31 Mexico 24 28 36 39 36 34 37 32 Saint Lucia NA NA 49 45 47 42 38 33 Saint Vincent and the Grenadines 36 52 40 56 83 40 42 34 Maldives 37 54 53 50 53 41 43 35 Belize 38 49 47 53 50 45 44 36 Romania 40 50 56 63 59 51 47 37 Peru 50 55 59 57 54 50 46 38 Eswatini 45 46 48 55 58 56 51 39 Bulgaria 42 47 54 47 57 55 52 40 Belarus 35 45 43 43 45 48 50 41 Kazakhstan 43 40 41 42 46 47 54 42 301 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Table 15 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Colombia 34 39 44 44 49 52 55 43 Tunisia 41 43 50 52 52 49 48 44 Bolivia (Plurinational State of) NA 62 64 66 62 59 56 45 Uruguay 48 32 69 36 87 44 94 46 Serbia 44 42 51 51 55 57 53 47 Bhutan 65 68 70 71 70 61 58 48 Ukraine 53 53 46 49 63 64 66 49 Iran (Islamic Republic of) 32 38 39 54 51 58 45 50 Indonesia 33 37 42 67 85 75 79 51 Lebanon 61 64 63 62 66 63 62 52 Republic of Moldova 52 56 61 59 65 67 65 53 Cabo Verde 51 57 62 65 68 68 61 54 Georgia 63 69 71 74 73 78 64 55 Albania 58 63 66 69 67 70 63 56 Mongolia 59 60 58 60 64 66 59 57 Uzbekistan NA NA NA 68 61 60 57 58 Sri Lanka 69 73 77 81 76 77 60 59 Lesotho 57 58 67 70 71 72 71 60 El Salvador NA 65 NA 72 72 71 67 61 Djibouti 70 66 75 73 78 73 73 62 Honduras NA NA NA 75 74 74 69 63 Lao People’s Democratic Republic 74 78 81 83 81 81 74 64 Nicaragua 67 75 76 78 77 80 70 65 Guatemala 64 71 74 79 79 79 77 66 Sao Tome and Principe NA 70 73 76 82 84 75 67 Kyrgyzstan 71 74 72 77 80 83 76 68 Philippines 78 85 93 88 75 76 72 69 Azerbaijan 56 61 65 61 60 65 68 70 Myanmar NA 88 NA NA NA NA NA 71 Tajikistan 72 77 78 86 84 85 80 72 Nepal 68 76 79 85 88 86 78 73 Ghana NA 81 88 80 86 82 84 74 Mauritania 76 82 86 89 90 90 89 75 Benin 73 79 82 87 89 87 81 76 Togo 77 80 85 92 91 88 85 77 Senegal 81 87 87 91 95 89 93 78 Gambia 80 84 83 93 92 93 87 79 Cameroon NA 86 90 NA 94 NA 86 80 Burundi 75 NA NA NA NA 97 97 81 Cote d’Ivoire 92 92 96 99 98 96 91 82 Cambodia 79 83 89 94 93 92 90 83 Rwanda NA NA NA NA NA NA 88 84 302 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 Table 15 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Guinea 87 90 92 95 97 95 96 85 Burkina Faso 91 95 97 100 99 99 98 86 Mali 90 93 95 101 100 100 100 87 Niger 93 97 98 102 101 101 101 88 Bangladesh 84 NA NA NA NA NA NA 89 United Republic of Tanzania 88 98 100 103 102 103 102 90 Pakistan 95 101 102 105 105 105 103 91 Norway NA NA NA 1 1 1 1 NA Switzerland NA NA 4 3 6 NA 2 NA Malta NA 15 17 16 18 18 13 NA Japan NA NA NA 18 20 NA 14 NA Singapore NA NA NA NA NA NA 15 NA Italy 11 14 15 19 21 17 18 NA Brunei Darussalam NA NA 18 NA 24 NA 20 NA Grenada NA NA NA NA NA NA 23 NA Costa Rica NA 34 32 32 34 25 25 NA Fiji 55 59 60 64 56 62 49 NA India 96 100 NA 104 103 104 82 NA Sierra Leone NA NA 84 90 NA 91 83 NA Central African Republic 85 89 91 NA NA NA 92 NA Liberia NA NA NA NA 96 94 95 NA Chad 89 94 NA 96 NA 98 99 NA Iceland NA 3 5 4 7 2 NA NA Luxembourg NA NA 2 NA 3 3 NA NA Belgium NA NA NA NA 10 7 NA NA Turkey NA NA 37 41 42 36 NA NA Micronesia NA NA NA NA NA 43 NA NA Ecuador 46 51 52 48 48 46 NA NA South Africa NA NA NA NA NA 53 NA NA Dominica NA NA NA NA NA 54 NA NA Vanuatu NA NA NA NA NA 69 NA NA South Sudan NA 96 NA NA NA 102 NA NA Denmark NA NA NA NA 2 NA NA NA United States of America NA 7 7 8 9 NA NA NA Namibia 31 NA NA NA 69 NA NA NA Saudi Arabia 49 12 99 10 104 NA NA NA Viet Nam 47 41 55 58 NA NA NA NA Zimbabwe NA NA 80 82 NA NA NA NA Comoros NA NA NA 84 NA NA NA NA Mozambique NA NA 94 97 NA NA NA NA Uganda 86 91 NA 98 NA NA NA NA Paraguay NA NA 57 NA NA NA NA NA 303 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 of education. As shown in this index, significant worldwide disparities are observed in guaranteeing basic access to education, with developed countries substantially outper- forming developing countries. According to UN treaties, if individual countries do not have the resources to fulfill this obligation, “the international community has a clear obli- gation to assist”. Education is linked to another issue area covered by this project, human- itarian aid, which we discuss in another section of this report. Table 15 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Guyana 62 67 68 NA NA NA NA NA Kenya NA NA 101 NA NA NA NA NA Panama NA 48 NA NA NA NA NA NA Timor-Leste 66 72 NA NA NA NA NA NA Ethiopia 94 99 NA NA NA NA NA NA San Marino 13 NA NA NA NA NA NA NA Congo 54 NA NA NA NA NA NA NA Solomon Islands 60 NA NA NA NA NA NA NA Guinea-Bissau 82 NA NA NA NA NA NA NA Angola 83 NA NA NA NA NA NA NA Fig. 7 2017 index ranking of education on a world map 304 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 3.9 Issue 8: Public Health Health is primarily viewed by many as a domestic issue. The connections can be unclear between public health as a domestic public good and public health as a country’ contribu- tion to the global public good. The rational is that when one country progresses in public health, the country improves the whole world’s public health. Notably, the global commu- nity, especially the United Nations, has taken many measures (e.g., sustainable development goals) to solve public health problems to promote an equal, just, and prosperous world. 3.9.1 Dimensions and Indicators Although public health has normally been considered a national public good, its deficit constitutes inequality at the global level, and its improvement has positive implications for global justice. In measuring public health, we first focus on health-related perfor- mance by measuring the protection of an individual’s right to health and then focus on a government’s effort to improve its health system. The dimensions we use include life expectancy, health infrastructure, key diseases, and governmental expenditure (Table 16). These data are from the WHO and covers 195 countries from 2010 to 2017. In this study, a major challenge is the missing value problem. Thus, data quality is unsatisfactory. Many countries, especially developing countries, have incomplete public health data. 3.9.2 Results In this section, we present the ranking result of countries’ contributions to global justice from the public health perspective (Table 17). The Table 17 shows 9 years of results— from 2010 to 2017—in 195 countries. Table 17 shows that China, Finland, France, Sweden, the United Kingdom, Germany, and Norway have consistently performed the best in of global justice from a public health perspective. India and some African countries do not perform well in this regard and have much more to do to catch up. The general trend is that countries tend to do better when their economy is more developed. Thus, developing countries still have a many improve- ments to make in public health (Fig. 8). In 2017, Sweden, Finland, China, New Zealand, and the United Kingdom are the top five countries in promoting global justice from a public health perspective. China is the only developing country among the top five nations. 3.10 Issue 9: Protection of Women and Children Protection of women and children is essential for global justice. Each country’s con- tribution (e.g., finical contribution) to women and children is difficult to distinguish from other issues such as public health, education, and poverty. Thus, we focus on the performance dimension, because it is measurable. Additionally, the protection issue concerns gender inequality and children’s situations. First, we use the ratio of health, demography, economic status, and political empowerment between male and female to measure gender inequality from the perspective of gender-based gaps in resources 305 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Ta bl e 16 D at a on p ub lic h ea lth C at eg or y D im en si on In di ca to rs D at a so ur ce C ov er ag e Pe rf or m an ce L ife e xp ec ta nc y L ife e xp ec ta nc y at b ir th (y ea rs ), bo th s ex es W H O 16 9– 17 8 (2 01 0– 20 17 ) L ife e xp ec ta nc y at a ge 6 0 (y ea rs ), bo th s ex es In fa nt m or ta lit y ra te (p ro ba bi lit y of d yi ng b et w ee n bi rt h an d ag e 1 pe r 1 00 0 liv e bi rt hs ), bo th se xe s N eo na ta l m or ta lit y ra te (p er 1 00 0 liv e bi rt hs ), bo th s ex es U nd er fi ve m or ta lit y ra te (p ro ba bi lit y of d yi ng b y ag e 5 pe r 1 00 0 liv e bi rt hs ), bo th s ex es A du lt m or ta lit y ra te (p ro ba bi lit y of d yi ng b et w ee n 15 a nd 6 0  ye ar s pe r 1 00 0 po pu la tio n) , b ot h se xe s H ea lth in fr as tr uc tu re Po pu la tio n us in g at le as t b as ic d ri nk in g- w at er s er vi ce s (% ), to ta l Po pu la tio n us in g at le as t b as ic s an ita tio n se rv ic es (% ), to ta l Po pu la tio n pr ac tic in g op en d ef ec at io n (% ), to ta l K ey d is ea se s Tr ea tm en t s uc ce ss ra te : n ew T B c as es Tu be rc ul os is e ff ec tiv e tr ea tm en t c ov er ag e (% ) R ai se d bl oo d pr es su re (S B P ≥ 1 40 o r D B P ≥ 9 0) (a ge -s ta nd ar di ze d es tim at e) 1 8  ye ar s, b ot h se xe s R ai se d fa st in g bl oo d gl uc os e (≥ 7 .0  m m ol /L o r o n m ed ic at io n) (a ge -s ta nd ar di ze d es tim at e) 18  y ea rs , b ot h se xe s In ci de nc e of tu be rc ul os is (p er 1 00 ,0 00 p op ul at io n pe r y ea r) , b ot h se xe s C on tr ib ut io n E xp en di tu re O ut -o f- po ck et e xp en di tu re a s a pe rc en ta ge o f t ot al e xp en di tu re o n he al th O ut -o f- po ck et e xp en di tu re (O O P) p er c ap ita in U S$ C ur re nt h ea lth e xp en di tu re (C H E ) p er c ap ita in U S$ D om es tic g en er al g ov er nm en t h ea lth e xp en di tu re (G G H E -D ) p er c ap ita in U S$ D om es tic p ri va te h ea lth e xp en di tu re (P V T- D ) p er c ap ita in U S$ 306 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 Table 17 Country ranking in the public health aspect of promoting global justice Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 China 8 6 5 4 3 4 1 1 United States of America 4 4 4 5 4 3 2 2 Sweden 13 5 6 3 5 5 3 3 Germany 7 9 10 9 8 6 5 4 Austria 12 12 13 12 12 12 6 5 Belgium 10 11 12 11 11 10 8 6 Denmark 5 8 9 8 7 7 7 7 Singapore 22 21 19 21 21 18 12 8 United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland 21 20 20 17 14 9 10 9 Republic of Korea 24 24 23 23 23 19 14 10 Italy 15 15 15 18 19 17 13 11 Iceland 18 17 17 19 15 11 11 12 Luxembourg 3 7 7 6 6 8 9 13 Cyprus 23 22 22 24 25 25 20 14 Venezuela (Bolivarian Republic of) 31 35 31 32 29 26 21 15 Spain 19 19 21 22 22 21 18 16 Australia 9 10 8 10 10 27 17 17 Norway 2 2 2 2 2 2 4 18 Azerbaijan 32 31 30 29 28 28 24 19 Malta 27 27 26 27 26 24 22 20 Netherlands 16 16 16 16 18 16 16 21 New Zealand 25 25 24 25 24 22 19 22 Canada 11 13 11 14 16 13 15 23 Mexico 29 29 28 30 31 30 26 24 Russian Federation 39 36 34 33 32 32 27 25 Georgia 33 32 33 34 36 36 30 26 Sudan 70 66 48 48 45 40 36 27 Cambodia 62 56 38 37 34 35 34 28 France 17 18 18 20 20 20 23 29 Iran (Islamic Republic of) 30 30 32 42 40 37 35 30 Yemen 42 42 45 41 37 49 29 31 Grenada 40 39 43 44 43 39 37 32 Bangladesh 65 63 56 52 49 51 41 33 Bahamas 35 40 37 45 47 34 33 34 Morocco 46 45 47 46 44 47 38 35 Trinidad and Tobago 51 44 36 40 38 33 32 36 Bulgaria 52 46 50 43 42 44 39 37 Portugal 26 26 29 31 30 31 28 38 Argentina 87 83 70 60 59 48 43 39 Ecuador 48 52 40 51 39 38 42 40 Saint Lucia 38 33 44 35 57 42 40 41 Armenia 53 76 46 47 48 45 46 42 307 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Table 17 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Sierra Leone 57 54 54 61 60 55 48 43 Mauritius 55 55 52 53 46 50 45 44 Barbados 44 43 42 49 50 46 44 45 Tajikistan 43 53 53 55 51 52 50 46 Paraguay 45 47 55 58 54 54 49 47 Chile 41 37 39 38 41 41 47 48 Guatemala 54 48 49 57 56 58 52 49 Albania 56 59 57 62 53 56 54 50 Egypt 47 50 51 54 55 59 53 51 Brazil 34 34 35 39 35 43 51 52 Serbia 66 64 67 63 65 63 56 53 Montenegro 73 73 82 67 64 61 55 54 Ukraine 80 72 73 70 68 64 58 55 Honduras 74 67 66 77 79 70 61 56 Japan 6 3 3 7 9 23 31 57 Philippines 75 69 69 71 77 85 67 58 Malaysia 93 81 84 79 76 78 59 59 Sri Lanka 79 74 72 89 87 73 66 60 Kazakhstan 69 68 59 50 58 60 57 61 Lebanon 37 38 62 66 69 62 64 62 Guinea-Bissau 108 86 89 90 80 84 70 63 Uzbekistan 83 82 77 78 85 76 69 64 Afghanistan 68 57 71 69 75 79 63 65 Hungary 58 58 61 65 67 67 65 66 Turkmenistan 89 95 94 95 84 81 72 67 Lithuania 71 70 60 59 52 57 60 68 Djibouti 105 101 107 102 117 101 80 69 Finland 14 14 14 13 13 14 25 70 Republic of Moldova 78 90 78 87 95 86 78 71 Mongolia 103 105 87 82 91 88 77 72 Bahrain 119 123 81 76 74 66 62 73 Nepal 106 111 99 86 90 91 76 74 Cameroon 61 106 65 64 62 74 74 75 Costa Rica 92 88 86 83 83 69 71 76 Panama 107 100 104 100 96 80 75 77 Tunisia 94 92 90 88 86 87 82 78 Viet Nam 64 60 83 81 78 83 81 79 Belarus 137 122 137 97 93 100 85 80 Latvia 36 41 41 36 33 53 68 81 United Arab Emirates 67 71 79 72 66 68 73 82 Estonia 88 96 92 80 71 75 79 83 Algeria 113 108 116 117 113 106 95 84 308 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 Table 17 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Nicaragua 124 119 98 93 105 98 91 85 Comoros 117 77 100 84 89 94 86 86 Togo 95 80 96 108 97 96 89 87 Mauritania 81 87 97 110 98 89 84 88 Mali 86 99 105 96 109 97 93 89 Central African Republic 110 102 102 104 100 102 94 90 Republic of North Macedonia 82 94 101 114 88 92 90 91 Lao People’s Democratic Republic 112 78 80 113 115 112 102 92 Antigua and Barbuda 101 109 111 112 108 109 96 93 Guyana 125 124 121 92 102 107 103 94 Peru 85 85 88 99 114 104 100 95 Uruguay 104 103 95 85 92 93 88 96 Slovakia 50 51 58 56 63 65 83 97 Czechia 63 65 76 73 73 82 87 98 Maldives 91 97 114 107 103 90 97 99 Saudi Arabia 111 114 112 111 101 95 101 100 Cote d’Ivoire 84 84 103 109 107 108 104 101 Slovenia 49 61 74 75 72 77 92 102 Haiti 140 148 142 131 128 120 109 103 Guinea 97 91 85 91 110 110 106 104 Turkey 126 116 118 116 111 113 107 105 Kyrgyzstan 114 117 117 115 104 99 99 106 El Salvador 109 110 113 120 119 114 114 107 Iraq 135 134 106 106 99 118 111 108 Kuwait 98 98 93 98 94 105 105 109 Jamaica 115 107 126 126 122 115 130 110 Indonesia 129 127 129 130 129 122 110 111 Bosnia and Herzegovina 102 104 108 101 106 111 108 112 Senegal 122 121 119 118 120 119 113 113 Qatar 77 93 110 103 82 72 98 114 Liberia 144 133 134 129 132 116 112 115 Uganda 155 152 131 143 138 129 121 116 Romania 123 125 127 123 124 121 116 117 Burkina Faso 141 118 124 135 126 127 120 118 Benin 120 126 120 119 118 123 117 119 Zambia 138 129 132 139 141 135 124 120 Colombia 128 128 133 134 131 130 122 121 Rwanda 143 142 139 142 142 132 125 122 Madagascar 127 135 125 144 121 136 118 123 Fiji 150 145 144 147 143 134 126 124 Chad 96 113 115 121 127 125 119 125 Belize 132 131 130 128 134 128 127 126 309 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Table 17 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Bolivia (Plurinational State of) 133 137 135 133 137 133 128 127 Cabo Verde 134 138 138 136 144 137 129 128 Myanmar 59 49 91 94 112 117 123 129 Niger 76 79 75 124 136 139 132 130 Bhutan 163 162 140 141 139 138 133 131 Dominican Republic 100 112 122 122 130 131 131 132 Saint Vincent and the Grenadines 146 147 64 146 61 164 115 133 Cuba 151 150 154 151 148 140 135 134 Equatorial Guinea 145 143 148 138 133 143 137 135 Suriname 154 154 152 154 151 146 143 136 Thailand 142 146 145 145 145 144 138 137 Jordan 130 132 136 132 135 141 136 138 Eswatini 156 155 159 159 159 151 140 139 Croatia 90 115 123 125 125 126 134 140 Congo 118 139 151 149 153 149 142 141 Kenya 116 136 155 153 156 152 146 142 Ghana 161 163 147 157 147 145 139 143 Lesotho 157 158 156 156 155 148 141 144 Namibia 160 159 160 160 161 157 147 145 Tonga 158 157 158 158 158 153 144 146 Oman 149 151 149 152 149 147 145 147 United Republic of Tanzania 159 160 170 169 168 160 152 148 Papua New Guinea 167 168 166 168 166 161 153 149 Burundi 148 149 153 155 152 156 149 150 Angola 153 156 157 162 154 158 151 151 Pakistan 136 140 146 148 150 155 150 152 Gambia 152 153 150 150 157 154 148 153 Vanuatu 170 169 168 166 170 166 158 154 Seychelles 165 164 164 164 163 159 155 155 Solomon Islands 173 171 172 173 172 168 160 156 Botswana 168 167 165 171 167 165 157 157 Samoa 164 165 163 165 165 163 156 158 Gabon 147 130 143 140 140 150 154 159 Malawi 171 173 171 172 171 167 161 160 Sao Tome and Principe 131 144 161 163 160 162 159 161 South Africa 172 172 173 174 173 170 162 162 Timor-Leste 166 166 167 167 164 169 163 163 Kiribati 174 174 175 176 174 171 164 164 Ethiopia 175 175 174 175 175 173 165 165 Mozambique 176 176 176 177 176 174 166 166 Democratic Republic of the Congo 169 170 169 170 169 172 167 167 Nigeria 177 177 177 178 177 175 168 168 310 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 and opportunities in countries. Second, we focus on the gender difference of children’s situations from the perspective of poverty, health, and education. 3.10.1 Dimensions and Indicators Table 18 reports the indicators used in protection of women and children. We use two data sources. The information on children’s health and demography is from the WHO, and the remainders are from the World Bank. Table 17 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 India 178 178 178 179 178 176 169 169 Switzerland 1 1 1 1 1 1 NA NA Ireland NA NA NA 15 17 15 NA NA Greece 20 23 25 28 27 29 NA NA Poland NA NA NA 74 70 71 NA NA Libya 99 89 109 105 116 103 NA NA Zimbabwe 121 120 128 127 123 124 NA NA Brunei Darussalam 139 141 141 137 146 142 NA NA South Sudan NA NA 63 68 81 NA NA NA Micronesia (Federated States of) 162 161 162 161 162 NA NA NA Israel 28 28 27 26 NA NA NA NA Syrian Arab Republic 60 62 68 NA NA NA NA NA Eritrea 72 75 NA NA NA NA NA NA Fig. 8 2017 index ranking of public health on a world map 311 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Ta bl e 18 D at a on th e pr ot ec tio n of w om en a nd c hi ld re n C at eg or y D im en si on s In di ca to rs D at a so ur ce C ov er ag e Pe rf or m an ce (w om en ) H ea lth a nd d em og ra ph y L ife e xp ec ta nc y at b ir th , r at io fe m al e to m al e (y ea rs ) W or ld B an k 15 5– 15 9 (2 01 0– 20 17 ) M at er na l m or ta lit y ra tio fe m al e to m al e (m od el ed e st im at e, p er 10 0, 00 0 liv e bi rt hs ) N um be r o f u nd er fi ve d ea th o f t ho us an ds , f em al e Se x ra tio a t b ir th (m al e to fe m al e bi rt hs ) E co no m ic s ta tu s U ne m pl oy m en t, fe m al e (% o f f em al e la bo r f or ce ) V ul ne ra bl e em pl oy m en t, ra tio fe m al e to m al e W ag e an d sa la ri ed w or ke rs , r at io fe m al e to m al e Po lit ic al s ta tu s Pr op or tio n of s ea ts h el d by w om en in n at io na l p ar lia m en ts (% ) Pe rf or m an ce (c hi ld re n) C hi ld re n he al th a nd d em og ra ph y N um be r o f d ea th s pe r 1 00 0 + (i nc lu de 1 3 in di ca to rs ) W H O Pr ev al en ce o f t hi nn es s am on g ch ild re n an d ad ol es ce nt s, B M I < − 2 st an da rd d ev ia tio ns b el ow th e m ed ia n (c ru de e st im at e) (% ) C hi ld re n ed uc at io n (t he e du ca tio na l di ff er en ce b et w ee n m al es a nd fe m al es ) Sc ho ol e nr ol lm en t, pr im ar y (g ro ss ), ge nd er p ar ity in de x (G PI ) W or ld B an k 312 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 3.10.2 Results The ranking results of countries’ contributions to global justice from the perspective of protection of women and children during 2010–2017 are presented in Table 19. Our robust result during 2010–2017 in Table 19 shows that countries such as China, the United States, Russia, Mexico, Germany, and other North European countries are at the top levels for protection of women and children, which suggests that these coun- tries do well in protecting their women and children. However, most African countries (e.g., Nigeria, Congo, Egypt, and Kenya) and South Asian countries (e.g., Pakistan, Indonesia, and Afghanistan) display low levels. The following map displays the results of the protection of women and children in 2017. The higher the ranking in the protection of women and children, and vice versa. As the map shows, generally, the countries in the south and west and the countries in Africa rank lower, whereas China, the North American countries, and European coun- tries rank high (Fig. 9). Protection of women and children focuses on gender inequality. As introduced in the methodology section, we use a population-based weighed score of indices to con- struct the score of this issue in the perspective of global justice. Thus, the highest score does not mean the top level of protection of women and children. For instance, China ranks first of all countries in this protection of women and children in 2017. However, this finding does not mean that China performs the best of all countries; by contrast, the finding means that China has made a sufficient number women and children far better off than the world average. 3.11 Global Justice Index: Our Main Results This study has the limitation of the dilemma of missing values. For instance, for cli- mate change, most notably, the data on carbon emission are unavailable after 2014. Another limitation is that, for anti-poverty, the data for many countries were unavail- able. Thus, we provide a global justice index that excludes anti-poverty (Table 20) and climate change (Table  21), respectively. Next, we provide a global justice index that excludes anti-poverty and climate change (Table 22). Finally, we provide a global jus- tice index of all nine issues (Table 23). In Table 20, the United States, the United Kingdom, Germany, China, and France rank as the top five in the global justice index that excludes anti-poverty. Other devel- oped countries such as Switzerland, Sweden, Italy, Canada, and Finland also perform well in the global justice index. Developing countries, by contrast, do not perform well in general. China is an exception, because this largest developing country ranks fourth in the index. Brazil’s ranking is approximately 15th, which is the second-highest coun- try in the developing world. The results in Table 20 imply that the more developed a country’s economy, the higher its ranking in the global justice index. Figure  10 also presents the index of global justice (except for anti-poverty) in 2014. In Table  21, the United States, the United Kingdom, Germany, Italy, France, and other developed countries perform well in the global justice index except for climate change. The United States ranks the highest in the index. Among developing countries, 313 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Table 19 Country ranking in protection of women and children Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 China 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 United States of America 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 2 Russian Federation 3 3 3 3 3 5 5 3 Mexico 7 6 5 5 5 3 3 4 Germany 5 4 4 4 4 4 4 5 United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland 6 7 7 8 7 6 6 6 France 8 8 6 7 8 8 8 7 Italy 9 9 8 9 10 9 9 8 Spain 10 12 12 14 13 12 11 9 Argentina 11 10 10 11 11 11 10 10 Poland 16 15 15 16 15 14 12 11 Republic of Korea 12 11 9 12 12 13 13 12 Canada 14 14 13 15 14 15 15 13 Ukraine 19 19 17 20 16 16 16 14 Australia 17 17 16 17 19 18 18 15 Viet Nam 23 22 11 22 20 17 17 16 Brazil 139 140 20 10 9 10 14 17 Thailand 15 13 14 13 17 33 19 18 Netherlands 18 18 19 19 21 20 20 19 Saudi Arabia 60 54 45 24 29 23 27 20 Philippines 13 16 18 18 18 19 21 21 Sweden 26 24 23 23 22 21 22 22 Kazakhstan 31 30 26 27 25 22 26 23 Cuba 24 21 21 21 24 25 25 24 Belgium 27 25 24 25 23 24 24 25 Romania 35 41 38 35 35 31 31 26 Belarus 28 26 25 26 26 26 23 27 Syrian Arab Republic 70 37 35 28 28 28 29 28 Colombia 58 108 110 62 27 27 28 29 Czechia 29 28 28 31 30 29 32 30 Portugal 42 33 39 40 34 30 30 31 Israel 41 40 40 39 42 34 34 32 Dominican Republic 109 62 63 46 45 54 40 33 Austria 34 32 34 33 33 32 33 34 Finland 38 35 36 34 39 37 35 35 Norway 36 36 37 36 40 39 36 36 Denmark 37 38 42 41 43 41 37 37 Switzerland 39 39 41 42 41 40 39 38 Bulgaria 44 44 44 43 50 45 46 39 Peru 25 29 43 67 55 46 38 40 Serbia 52 55 49 52 46 44 45 41 Ireland 47 49 50 50 54 52 47 42 314 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 Table 19 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Venezuela 40 27 27 30 31 38 61 43 Hungary 43 43 48 44 44 43 44 44 Chile 49 51 56 49 49 48 52 45 Tunisia 55 64 60 54 47 50 51 46 New Zealand 45 45 47 45 52 51 49 47 Slovakia 50 50 52 51 56 57 53 48 Bolivia 105 105 105 109 58 53 48 49 Malaysia 22 20 22 29 32 42 50 50 Costa Rica 46 47 51 48 57 58 54 51 Kyrgyzstan 51 53 57 57 59 60 57 52 Senegal 72 46 29 56 53 47 59 53 Lebanon 104 81 76 60 63 64 60 54 Ecuador 30 31 31 38 36 36 43 55 Kuwait 57 59 58 55 62 62 56 56 Uzbekistan 33 34 33 37 38 56 58 57 Republic of Moldova 54 56 59 58 60 59 62 58 Nicaragua 61 48 53 59 61 61 64 59 Lithuania 56 61 62 61 64 63 63 60 Tajikistan 59 63 67 63 65 65 65 61 Croatia 53 57 66 64 66 69 67 62 Slovenia 62 58 68 65 68 66 66 63 Rwanda 32 42 46 53 51 49 55 64 Uruguay 67 68 73 69 69 70 69 65 Panama 78 66 74 73 67 67 68 66 Greece 48 52 61 71 71 71 75 67 Qatar 64 69 69 66 70 73 71 68 Mongolia 77 74 72 70 74 74 72 69 Estonia 65 67 71 72 76 75 73 70 Latvia 66 65 70 68 73 72 70 71 Trinidad and Tobago 69 70 75 74 77 76 77 72 Albania 96 82 94 93 88 84 81 73 Georgia 73 76 85 81 81 78 76 74 Republic of North Macedonia 74 77 79 77 79 77 79 75 El Salvador 99 88 81 88 75 68 78 76 Cyprus 68 72 78 76 80 82 80 77 Mauritius 71 71 77 75 78 79 82 78 Iceland 75 78 82 82 86 83 83 79 Malta 80 79 86 83 85 85 85 80 Bahrain 79 73 80 78 83 81 84 81 Montenegro 83 80 83 84 87 87 87 82 Luxembourg 76 75 84 85 84 86 86 83 Suriname 86 84 89 87 90 88 89 84 315 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Table 19 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Armenia 101 101 102 105 105 102 98 85 Barbados 84 83 87 86 89 89 90 86 Saint Vincent and the Grenadines 90 89 91 90 91 90 92 87 Samoa 88 87 92 92 92 91 91 88 Tonga 89 90 93 91 93 92 93 89 Brunei Darussalam NA NA NA NA NA NA 94 90 Cabo Verde 97 94 99 99 100 98 96 91 Belize 95 96 97 96 99 97 100 92 Vanuatu 91 91 95 94 95 95 97 93 Fiji 85 85 88 89 94 93 95 94 Sao Tome and Principe 93 93 96 95 97 96 99 95 Sri Lanka 81 104 65 79 82 100 104 96 Solomon Islands 94 95 98 97 102 101 101 97 Guyana 87 86 90 98 98 99 102 98 Maldives 98 99 101 102 103 104 105 99 Timor-Leste 100 100 100 101 101 103 103 100 Bhutan 92 98 103 103 106 105 106 101 Paraguay 106 103 107 80 104 94 107 102 Comoros 103 109 104 106 108 106 109 103 Djibouti 111 106 108 107 109 108 110 104 Honduras 63 60 64 100 96 80 108 105 Equatorial Guinea 108 107 109 108 110 110 111 106 Botswana 113 111 112 110 111 112 113 107 Azerbaijan 102 97 111 114 112 116 117 108 Oman 110 102 106 104 107 107 114 109 Eswatini 119 116 116 113 114 113 115 110 Namibia 114 112 115 116 115 111 112 111 Lesotho 115 114 114 112 113 114 116 112 Gambia 112 110 113 115 116 115 118 113 Cambodia 121 119 121 121 117 109 119 114 Congo 126 123 118 120 121 121 122 115 Lao People’s Democratic Republic 124 118 120 119 122 122 121 116 Mauritania 116 115 117 118 119 119 120 117 Algeria 136 131 55 47 48 55 74 118 Burundi 122 122 123 122 123 123 124 119 Guatemala 117 92 119 117 118 120 125 120 Nepal 21 23 30 111 120 117 123 121 Togo 127 126 126 123 125 124 127 122 Madagascar 128 127 125 126 126 126 128 123 Central African Republic 132 132 132 125 128 128 131 124 Malawi 125 125 124 127 130 129 132 125 Papua New Guinea 130 128 127 129 127 131 129 126 316 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 Table 19 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Uganda 107 117 122 128 129 127 130 127 Sierra Leone NA 130 129 130 NA 133 133 128 Zambia 129 129 130 131 134 136 134 129 Turkey 141 135 133 134 131 130 136 130 United Republic of Tanzania 120 120 131 137 133 132 135 131 Benin 131 134 135 132 135 137 138 132 Iran 145 145 142 139 132 134 139 133 Morocco 137 133 134 133 136 138 140 134 Myanmar 133 137 136 136 139 135 137 135 Burkina Faso 138 138 140 138 137 140 143 136 Guinea 135 136 137 135 138 139 142 137 South Africa 142 141 139 142 140 142 141 138 Niger 143 142 141 140 141 143 144 139 Ghana 134 139 138 141 142 141 145 140 India 155 155 152 150 152 153 150 141 Mozambique 140 143 143 147 145 145 146 142 Cameroon 146 147 146 143 143 144 147 143 Bangladesh 20 NA NA NA NA NA NA 144 Chad 147 146 145 146 146 147 148 145 Mali 144 144 144 144 144 146 149 146 Ethiopia 151 150 149 152 151 151 151 147 Yemen 150 149 148 149 148 150 152 148 Kenya 148 148 147 148 147 149 153 149 Afghanistan 152 151 150 151 149 152 154 150 Indonesia 4 5 54 145 150 154 156 151 Egypt 153 153 151 153 153 156 155 152 Democratic Republic of the Congo 154 154 153 154 154 155 157 153 Pakistan 156 156 155 155 155 157 158 154 Nigeria 157 157 154 156 156 158 159 155 Japan NA NA NA 6 6 7 7 NA United Arab Emirates NA NA 32 32 37 35 41 NA Bahamas 82 NA NA NA NA NA 88 NA Liberia NA 124 NA NA 124 125 126 NA Democratic People’s Republic of Korea NA NA NA NA NA 118 NA NA Angola 149 152 NA NA NA 148 NA NA Turkmenistan NA NA NA NA 72 NA NA NA Zimbabwe NA NA 128 124 NA NA NA NA Eritrea 123 121 NA NA NA NA NA NA Gabon NA 113 NA NA NA NA NA NA Guinea-Bissau 118 NA NA NA NA NA NA NA 317 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 China, Slovenia, and Mexico’s rankings are notable. China ranks fourth in the years of 2011, 2012, 2014, and 2015. However, the problem is that we only have ranking results of approximately 40 countries from 2010 through 2017. Figure 11 also shows the index of global justice (except for climate change) in 2017. Table  22 shows the results of the global justice index without considering climate change and anti-poverty from 2010 to 2017. This table presents approximately 100 coun- tries’ ranking results. Once again, the United States, Germany, the United Kingdom, China, and France rank as the top five in the global justice index that excludes climate change and anti-poverty. China performs best in the developing world, followed by Rwanda, another developing country, in 2017. Other developing countries such as Bangladesh, Brazil, Nepal, and Cyprus rank in the top 20, as well. Figure 12 also shows the index of global justice (except for climate change and anti-poverty) in 2017. Table  23 presents the global justice index with nine issues areas covered. The United States, the United Kingdom, Germany, China, and France rank as the top five in the global justice index. China is the highest ranking developing country and the United States performs best in the index. Other developed countries that rank among the top 20 include Switzerland, Norway, Sweden, Italy, Finland, Canada, Denmark, Belgium, Spain, Ireland, and Luxembourg. In the developing world, Brazil, Russia, Mexico, Slovenia, and Costa Rica have also done well in the index. We compare Tables  20, 21, 22, and 23, and observe that most countries’ rankings are consistent in these tables. For example, the United States always ranks first in these results. Similarly, China consistently ranks among the top of the developing countries. This Fig. 9 2017 index ranking of protection of women and children on a world map 318 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 Table 20 Global Justice Index (except for anti-poverty) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 United States of America 1 1 1 1 1 United Kingdom of Great Brit- ain and Northern Ireland 3 3 3 2 2 Germany 2 2 2 3 3 China 7 5 5 5 4 France 4 4 4 4 5 Switzerland NA NA 6 6 6 Norway NA NA NA 7 7 Sweden 9 9 7 8 8 Italy 5 7 9 10 9 Finland 10 10 10 11 10 Canada 8 8 8 9 11 Denmark NA NA NA NA 12 Spain 6 6 11 12 13 Belgium NA NA NA NA 14 Japan NA NA NA 14 15 Brazil 12 12 12 15 16 Australia 11 11 13 13 17 Nepal 64 13 15 17 18 New Zealand NA NA NA 16 19 Ukraine 52 59 57 55 20 Luxembourg NA NA 14 NA 21 Ghana NA 73 18 23 22 Russian Federation 14 14 16 19 23 Ireland NA NA NA 18 24 Senegal 19 20 21 25 25 Portugal 13 15 17 24 26 Uruguay 15 16 23 20 27 India 68 40 NA 21 28 Iceland NA 22 19 22 29 Mexico 18 19 22 28 30 Slovenia 16 18 20 27 31 United Republic of Tanzania 26 28 39 32 32 Cambodia 33 33 32 33 33 Costa Rica NA 21 24 29 34 Cameroon NA 45 46 NA 35 Estonia 21 25 29 34 36 Togo 49 51 42 41 37 Latvia 25 29 26 30 38 Argentina 23 23 27 31 39 Chile 28 30 33 35 40 Guatemala 22 24 30 36 41 Hungary 32 32 35 40 42 319 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Table 20 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 Peru 24 26 34 39 43 Cyprus 20 27 31 37 44 Indonesia 17 17 25 38 45 Ecuador 41 44 44 47 46 Lithuania 40 41 40 43 47 Benin 37 48 48 48 48 Albania 29 35 38 45 49 Poland NA NA NA 44 50 Bulgaria 36 43 43 46 51 Honduras NA NA NA 51 52 Malaysia 39 38 37 49 53 Sri Lanka 38 42 50 50 54 Croatia 30 46 49 53 55 Nicaragua 45 56 51 56 56 Romania 42 53 55 59 57 Philippines 31 36 41 54 58 Georgia 35 47 52 57 59 Serbia 48 58 59 64 60 Niger 57 62 61 65 61 Turkey NA NA 45 52 62 El Salvador NA 50 NA 61 63 Tajikistan 43 49 53 60 64 Pakistan 27 37 63 58 65 Colombia 44 55 56 63 66 Mauritius 46 57 60 67 67 Malta NA 60 62 62 68 Mongolia 62 70 69 69 69 Belarus 59 65 68 70 70 Azerbaijan 50 61 65 72 71 Bolivia (Plurinational State of) NA 63 66 73 72 Namibia 51 NA NA NA 73 Kyrgyzstan 55 64 70 74 74 Tunisia 54 67 71 76 75 Republic of Moldova 61 68 73 77 76 Kazakhstan 63 69 74 78 77 Saudi Arabia 56 34 67 26 78 Lebanon 58 66 72 79 79 Qatar NA NA NA 75 80 Republic of Korea 65 71 75 80 81 Bahrain NA 72 NA NA 82 Iran (Islamic Republic of) 69 75 76 82 83 Israel 34 52 47 42 NA Viet Nam 66 74 54 66 NA 320 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 comparison implies that our results are robust and scientific. Figure 13 also shows the index of global justice in 2014. 4 Conclusion This paper focuses on a measurement and operationalization of global justice that identifies, evaluates, and assesses the performance of nation states in conducting pro- jects and endeavors to promote justice at the global level. First, we briefly introduced our conceptualization of global justice and our development of the theoretical frame- work, which provides a basis for the subsequent measurement. Through the synthesis of three approaches—rights-based, goods-based, and virtue-based—embedded in the historical discussion of global justice, we proposed the principles of CBDR-RC and CDDR to further determine nine issue areas of crucial importance: climate change, peacekeeping, humanitarian aid, counter-terrorism, cross-national criminal police cooperation, anti-poverty, education, public health, and the protection of women and children. By collecting, processing, and normalizing the data, we generate ranks for each issue area and aggregate them to create the final index. Through various visu- alization tools, we provide a visual exhibition of the performance and contribution of each nation state in the areas of global justice, the regional comparisons, and the trends of change over time. Our result shows that the United States, the United Kingdom, Germany, China, and France rank as the top five in the global justice index. The United States undoubtedly ranks first in the index. China ranks the highest among developing countries. In gen- eral, developed countries have performed better than their counterparts in the develop- ing world. This finding implies that the more developed and wealthier a country, the higher its ranking. The contribution of this paper can be summarized as follows: (1) the global justice index is the first attempt to measure the performance and contribution of nation states to enhance justice at the global level; (2) the index presents a rich, comprehensive Table 20 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 Mozambique NA NA 64 68 NA Zimbabwe NA NA 36 71 NA Uzbekistan NA NA NA 81 NA Paraguay NA NA 28 NA NA Kenya NA NA 58 NA NA Myanmar NA 31 NA NA NA Panama NA 39 NA NA NA Ethiopia 60 54 NA NA NA Congo 47 NA NA NA NA Bangladesh 53 NA NA NA NA Angola 67 NA NA NA NA 321 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Table 21 Global Justice Index (except for climate change) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 United States of America 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 Germany 3 3 3 3 3 3 2 2 United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland 2 2 2 2 2 2 3 3 France 4 5 5 4 5 5 4 4 Sweden 8 9 9 10 9 8 8 5 Canada 7 8 8 7 10 10 6 6 Finland 9 10 11 12 12 13 11 7 Republic of Korea 34 43 46 43 46 15 10 8 Spain 6 7 10 11 13 14 9 9 Russian Federation 15 18 15 29 21 20 14 10 Brazil 11 11 13 13 19 17 15 11 Portugal 16 12 16 19 24 21 18 12 Mexico 19 14 17 17 20 22 12 13 Slovenia 17 16 27 21 29 25 24 14 Cyprus 36 NA NA NA 23 48 NA 15 Belarus 35 35 45 48 47 19 33 16 Indonesia 23 20 24 34 34 35 19 17 Latvia 25 22 22 25 28 31 22 18 Honduras NA NA NA 38 39 37 32 19 Serbia 10 38 23 24 43 45 13 20 Hungary 21 19 21 31 27 30 23 21 Peru 28 30 35 36 35 36 26 22 Georgia 24 32 42 41 45 43 28 23 Estonia 12 21 36 23 41 39 21 24 Lithuania 26 26 28 28 25 24 20 25 Argentina 30 28 18 20 22 32 17 26 Kyrgyzstan 20 41 33 35 50 33 37 27 Uruguay 27 27 20 15 38 23 25 28 Romania 22 23 31 30 36 40 30 29 El Salvador NA 31 NA 40 37 42 27 30 Colombia 31 40 44 39 48 46 35 31 Bolivia (Plurinational State of) NA 44 40 42 44 41 34 32 Republic of Moldova 33 42 38 45 52 38 31 33 Kazakhstan 32 45 39 46 30 28 16 34 Ukraine 37 34 34 44 17 11 36 35 Italy 5 6 6 9 8 7 5 NA Norway NA NA NA 6 7 6 7 NA Costa Rica NA 29 30 26 32 29 29 NA Iran (Islamic Republic of) NA NA NA NA 49 47 38 NA Malta NA 15 26 47 51 NA 39 NA China NA 4 4 5 4 4 NA NA Belgium NA NA NA NA 14 9 NA NA 322 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 picture of global justice that offers a guide to global justice for individuals who want to observe annual achievement and changes over time; (3) the index is a barometer for the international community to implement and monitor global justice in different issue areas, enabling international organizations and policymakers to target resources and design policies more effectively; and (4) the index can be used as an analytical tool to compare relevant global justice issues across nations and included as a dependent vari- able or independent variable in causal analysis. Notably, this study has several limitations: (1) based on the previous theoretical research, we used nine issues to measure global justice. We excluded refugees and other issues which might have also been highly related to global justice for various reasons. (2) Because no theoretical research has provided the weight of the nine issues to global justice, we, in practice, assume that the nine issues equally con- tribute to global justice. How to weight the nine issues is a subject for further theo- retical research. (3) Due to data limitations, we did not include all countries in this study. For some issues, such as poverty, climate change, and education, the prob- lem of missing values is more serious. Thus, in further research, we will continue to collect data to overcome this problem. (4) The results of this study only apply to comparisons between countries in each year because of the various numbers of countries each year. Regarding our conclusion, a comparison of the global justice index across years is inappropriate. Table 21 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Luxembourg NA NA 12 NA 15 12 NA NA Iceland NA 13 14 16 18 16 NA NA Ireland NA NA NA 14 16 18 NA NA Poland NA NA NA 22 26 26 NA NA Ecuador 29 36 37 37 40 27 NA NA Turkey NA NA 25 27 31 34 NA NA Croatia 18 33 29 33 33 44 NA NA Switzerland NA NA 7 8 6 NA NA NA Denmark NA NA NA NA 11 NA NA NA Bulgaria 13 24 32 32 42 NA NA NA Israel 14 17 19 18 NA NA NA NA Paraguay NA NA 41 NA NA NA NA NA Mongolia NA 39 43 NA NA NA NA NA Pakistan NA 25 NA NA NA NA NA NA Panama NA 37 NA NA NA NA NA NA 323 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Table 22 Global Justice Index (except for of both climate change and anti-poverty) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 United States of America 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 Germany 3 3 3 3 3 3 2 2 United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland 2 2 2 2 2 2 3 3 China 6 4 4 4 4 4 4 4 France 4 5 5 5 5 5 5 5 Sweden 10 10 9 10 9 8 9 6 Canada 8 8 8 8 10 9 7 7 Australia 9 9 10 11 12 12 10 8 Spain 7 7 11 13 16 14 11 9 Finland 11 11 12 12 13 11 14 10 Republic of Korea 81 89 90 97 97 15 13 11 Rwanda NA NA NA NA NA NA 12 12 Bangladesh 55 NA NA NA NA NA NA 13 New Zealand NA NA NA 19 22 18 21 14 Russian Federation 14 13 15 20 24 21 20 15 Brazil 12 12 14 17 18 19 17 16 Nepal 82 21 21 23 23 20 18 17 Cyprus 13 16 17 26 29 23 25 18 Senegal 24 26 25 30 26 24 19 19 Argentina 18 20 18 25 28 26 26 20 Mexico 16 17 19 27 25 22 22 21 Portugal 15 18 20 29 31 28 30 22 Ghana NA 90 29 33 30 30 24 23 Burkina Faso 57 49 58 48 38 36 23 24 Indonesia 21 22 27 41 54 40 29 25 Chile 25 27 26 32 36 33 32 26 Slovenia 22 28 30 35 39 35 39 27 Qatar 17 23 22 24 32 25 37 28 Uruguay 20 19 24 22 34 32 33 29 Estonia 29 37 38 44 45 41 42 30 Togo 52 57 51 42 35 38 31 31 Hungary 31 30 35 43 47 44 44 32 Malaysia 28 31 31 38 44 48 41 33 Barbados 83 91 91 98 46 39 45 34 Mongolia 44 61 42 39 41 46 36 35 Latvia 27 32 34 36 42 43 48 36 United Republic of Tanzania 54 56 73 47 40 52 34 37 Cambodia 51 50 49 56 48 45 35 38 Ukraine 48 47 41 40 19 29 40 39 Lithuania 32 35 36 45 50 47 50 40 Mauritius 40 46 54 60 58 53 52 41 Oman NA NA NA NA NA NA NA 42 324 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 Table 22 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Mauritania 58 66 74 79 79 77 43 43 Serbia 41 45 52 58 60 55 49 44 Cuba 60 72 77 66 71 60 61 45 Bulgaria 38 41 50 57 63 58 56 46 Peru 36 38 43 55 62 59 51 47 Azerbaijan 30 34 39 53 53 51 53 48 Benin 35 42 46 46 49 50 38 49 Tunisia 37 52 57 65 68 61 57 50 Kazakhstan 42 44 44 51 61 57 59 51 Guatemala 39 39 48 61 64 62 58 52 Belarus 53 59 64 64 67 66 62 53 Romania 47 58 65 70 72 67 64 54 Cameroon NA 84 83 NA 51 NA 55 55 Albania 45 53 59 67 69 68 60 56 Lebanon 43 51 61 76 84 73 68 57 Honduras NA NA NA 69 73 70 65 58 Croatia 33 43 55 63 70 64 74 59 Republic of Moldova 50 60 60 68 75 72 71 60 Georgia 56 62 67 71 76 78 72 61 El Salvador NA 63 NA 73 77 75 69 62 Bahrain NA 69 72 74 83 69 73 63 Guinea 74 82 85 83 88 83 66 64 Burundi 89 NA NA NA NA 71 63 65 Nicaragua 61 70 70 72 78 79 75 66 Niger 66 68 62 62 56 63 47 67 Sri Lanka 62 65 69 75 74 74 76 68 Lao People’s Democratic Republic 63 64 71 78 81 81 78 69 Philippines 34 36 47 59 66 80 77 70 Tajikistan 59 67 76 77 80 82 79 71 Saint Vincent and the Grenadines 67 80 63 84 82 87 80 72 Belize 71 81 81 86 90 84 84 73 Lesotho 69 76 80 82 87 89 83 74 Kyrgyzstan 70 77 79 81 85 86 82 75 Maldives 87 94 95 93 96 94 87 76 Colombia 72 83 86 88 93 91 90 77 Uzbekistan NA NA NA 85 89 90 85 78 Pakistan 23 29 68 52 65 65 54 79 Bolivia NA 85 87 90 92 92 91 80 Mali 65 75 37 49 52 56 88 81 Gambia 73 79 82 87 91 93 89 82 Myanmar NA 74 NA NA NA NA NA 83 Sao Tome and Principe NA 78 88 91 94 95 92 84 325 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Table 22 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 2015 2016 2017 Iran (Islamic Republic of) 84 92 92 99 99 96 94 85 Bhutan 90 96 96 102 100 98 95 86 Italy 5 6 7 9 7 7 6 NA Norway NA NA NA 6 6 6 8 NA India 86 33 NA 21 27 27 15 NA Japan NA NA NA 14 15 NA 16 NA Singapore NA NA NA NA NA NA 27 NA Malta NA 25 28 31 33 31 28 NA Costa Rica NA 40 40 50 57 42 46 NA Sierra Leone NA NA 93 101 NA 76 67 NA Chad 77 88 NA 89 NA 88 70 NA Liberia NA NA NA NA 86 85 81 NA Central African Republic 46 48 66 NA NA NA 86 NA Fiji 88 95 94 100 98 97 93 NA Belgium NA NA NA NA 14 10 NA NA Luxembourg NA NA 13 NA 17 13 NA NA Iceland NA 15 16 18 21 16 NA NA Ireland NA NA NA 15 20 17 NA NA Poland NA NA NA 34 37 34 NA NA South Africa NA NA NA NA NA 37 NA NA Turkey NA NA 32 37 43 49 NA NA Ecuador 49 54 56 54 55 54 NA NA Switzerland NA NA 6 7 8 NA NA NA Denmark NA NA NA NA 11 NA NA NA Saudi Arabia 26 14 33 16 59 NA NA NA Namibia 68 NA NA NA 95 NA NA NA Israel 19 24 23 28 NA NA NA NA Viet Nam 85 93 78 80 NA NA NA NA Zimbabwe NA NA 53 92 NA NA NA NA Comoros NA NA NA 94 NA NA NA NA Uganda 78 87 NA 95 NA NA NA NA Mozambique NA NA 89 96 NA NA NA NA Paraguay NA NA 45 NA NA NA NA NA Guyana 64 71 75 NA NA NA NA NA Kenya NA NA 84 NA NA NA NA NA Panama NA 55 NA NA NA NA NA NA Ethiopia 80 73 NA NA NA NA NA NA Timor-Leste 76 86 NA NA NA NA NA NA Guinea-Bissau 75 NA NA NA NA NA NA NA Congo 79 NA NA NA NA NA NA NA Solomon Islands 91 NA NA NA NA NA NA NA Angola 92 NA NA NA NA NA NA NA 326 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 Table 23 Global Justice Index (all nine issues) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 United States of America 1 1 1 1 1 United Kingdom of Great Brit- ain and Northern Ireland 2 2 3 2 2 Germany 3 3 2 3 3 China NA 5 5 9 4 France 4 4 4 4 5 Switzerland NA NA 6 7 6 Norway NA NA NA 6 7 Sweden 8 9 7 5 8 Italy 5 8 9 10 9 Finland 9 10 10 12 10 Canada 7 7 8 8 11 Denmark NA NA NA NA 12 Spain 6 6 11 11 13 Belgium NA NA NA NA 14 Brazil 10 11 12 13 15 Ireland NA NA NA 17 16 Luxembourg NA NA 13 NA 17 Ukraine 37 37 38 44 18 Russian Federation 15 20 14 31 19 Mexico 24 15 17 20 20 Iceland NA 21 16 21 21 Slovenia 14 13 19 16 22 Portugal 16 12 15 15 23 Latvia 25 18 18 22 24 Costa Rica NA 17 22 19 25 Argentina 31 32 23 23 26 Hungary 21 19 21 29 27 Lithuania 28 26 26 28 28 Cyprus 36 NA NA NA 29 Poland NA NA NA 25 30 Croatia 17 33 29 33 31 Peru 27 25 27 30 32 Estonia 11 14 25 18 33 Uruguay 26 24 20 14 34 Indonesia 18 16 24 34 35 Romania 20 22 33 27 36 Honduras NA NA NA 36 37 El Salvador NA 28 NA 41 38 Turkey NA NA 32 35 39 Ecuador 30 34 35 38 40 Bulgaria 13 23 34 32 41 Colombia 29 35 36 39 42 327 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Table 23 (continued) Country 2010 2011 2012 2013 2014 Georgia 19 31 39 40 43 Serbia 12 41 28 24 44 Bolivia (Plurinational State of) NA 42 40 42 45 Kazakhstan 34 45 44 46 46 Republic of Korea 32 40 43 43 47 Belarus 35 38 46 47 48 Kyrgyzstan 23 39 37 37 49 Iran (Islamic Republic of) NA NA NA NA 50 Malta NA 29 41 48 51 Republic of Moldova 33 44 42 45 52 Israel 22 30 31 26 NA Paraguay NA NA 30 NA NA Mongolia NA 43 45 NA NA Pakistan NA 27 NA NA NA Panama NA 36 NA NA NA Fig. 10 2014 index ranking of global justice (except for anti-poverty) on a world map 328 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 Fig. 11 2017 index ranking of global justice (except for climate change) on a world map Fig. 12 2017 index ranking of global justice (except for both climate change and poverty) on a world map 329 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Acknowledgements The Fudan IAS acknowledges the generous support which it has received from institu- tions such as the Fudan University School of International Relations and Public Affairs, the Shanghai “Gao Feng” Disciplinary Supporting Funds, Global Policy, Rutgers University, as well as useful comments and suggestions on this report from the following individuals: Arthur Boutellis (International Peace Institute), Daniel Callies (UC San Diego), Jean Marc Coicaud (Rutgers University), Selda Dagistanli (Western Sydney University), Marco Dugato (Università Cattolica del Sacro Cuore), Sakiko Fukuda-Parr (The New School, New York), Yannick Glemarec (Executive Director, UN Green Climate Fund), Carlos Manuel Gradin Lago (UNU-WIDER, United Nations University World Institute for Development), Terry Lynn Karl (Stanford University), Milorad Kovacevic (Chief of Statistics, UN Human Development Report Office), Jane Mans- bridge (Harvard University), and Philippe Schmitter (European University Institute). We are also grateful for helpful advice, comments, and suggestions from Yannick Glemarec, Executive Director, UN Green Cli- mate Fund, and Milorad Kovacevic, Chief of Statistics, UN Human Development Report Office. This is a group project of Fudan IAS. All members of the group named as authors contributed equally to the study and ranked alphabetically. We want to thank our research assistants for their time and important contribu- tions in data collection and aggregation: Jingpu Chen, Xinyu Dai, Ziheng Guo, Xiaoyuan Li, Yawen Lin, Muye Nanshan, Zhenyu Wang, Xiaolan Xia, and Yuqing Zhang. We also thank Xi Lin for his coordination throughout the project, as well as other Fudan IAS fellows, Su Gu, Qingping Liu, and Guodong Sun, for their active participation in and valuable contributions to our ongoing interactive discussions from their dif- ferent perspectives, expertise, and knowledge. Finally, we also owe our thanks to the three anonymous peer reviewers for their valuable comments and constructive criticism. All errors remain ours. Compliance with ethical standards Conflict of interest On behalf of all authors, the corresponding author states that there is no conflict of inter- est. Authors have no financial or personal relationship with a third party whose interests could be positively or negatively influenced by the article’s content. Fig. 13 2014 index ranking of global justice on a world map 330 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 1 3 Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Com- mons licence, and indicate if changes were made.The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article’s Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article’s Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creat iveco mmons .org/licen ses/by/4.0/ References Arneson, R. 1989. Equality and Equal Opportunity for Welfare. Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition, Springer 56 (1): 77–93. Freeman, S. 2006. Book Review—Frontiers of Justice: The Capabilities Approach versus Contractarianism. Texas Law Review 85 (2): 385–430. Guo, S., et  al. 2019. Conceptualizing and Measuring Global Justice: Theories, Concepts, Principles and Indicators. Fudan Journal of the Humanities and Social Sciences 12 (4): 511–546. Mo, D. 2003. Mozi: Basic Writings. Translated by B. Watson. New York: Columbia University Press. Nussbaum, M. 2006. Frontiers of Justice: Disability, Nationality, Species Membership. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Nussbaum, M. 2011. Capabilities, Entitlements, Rights: Supplementation and Critique. Journal of Human Development and Capabilities 12 (1): 23–37. Rawls, J. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. Rawls, J. 1999. The Law of Peoples. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Richardson, H.S. 2006. Rawlsian Social-Contract Theory and the Severely Disabled. The Journal of Ethics. Springer 10 (4): 419–462. Universal Declaration of Human Rights (1948). http://www.un.org/en/unive rsal-decla ratio n-human -right s/ index .html. Yanfeng Gu (Ph.D. in Social Sciences) is a lecturer and research fellow at the Fudan Institute for Advanced Study in Social Sciences (IAS-Fudan). He received his Ph.D. degree in social sciences at the Hong Kong University of Science and Technology. His primary fields are development economics, economic history, political economy, public administration, and social policy. His research interests include market integration, culture, social trust, and migration. His work has appeared in Chinese Sociological Review, Journal of Chi- nese Political Science, Sociological Study (in Chinese), and other leading journals in area studies. Xuan Qin (Ph.D. degree in political science) is a lecturer and research fellow at the Fudan Institute for Advanced Study in Social Sciences (IAS-Fudan). She received her Ph.D. from the Nanyang Technologi- cal University (NTU Singapore). She is also a research assistant in the program of Participedia, which is developed by Archon Fung (Kennedy School of Government, Harvard University) and Mark E. Warren (Department of Political Science, University of British Columbia). Her current research interests include democratic theory, statistical analysis, and data visualization. She has published several articles in SSCI and CSSCI journals. She currently serves as an editor for the Chinese Political Science Review. Zhongyuan Wang (Ph.D. in Political Science and China Studies) is a lecturer and research fellow at the Fudan Institute for Advanced Study in Social Sciences (IAS-Fudan). He received his doctoral degree from Leiden University (The Netherlands) and was a lecturer in the Program of International Studies at Leiden University. His research interests include comparative political institutions, election studies, political rep- resentation, local politics and governance, European politics, and governmental big data. His work has appeared in European Political Science, China Information, and the Journal of Contemporary China. He currently serves as an editor for the Journal of Chinese Political Science. http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ http://www.un.org/en/universal-declaration-human-rights/index.html http://www.un.org/en/universal-declaration-human-rights/index.html 331 1 3 Chinese Political Science Review (2020) 5:253–331 Chunman Zhang (Ph.D. degree in political science) is a senior lecturer and research fellow at the Fudan Institute for Advanced Study in Social Sciences (IAS-Fudan). He received his doctoral degree from the Johns Hopkins University. His research interests are comparative politics, party politics, environmental gov- ernance, and international relations. He has published over 25 academic papers in both English and Chinese leading journals, such as Environmental Politics, Land Use Policy, Journal of Chinese Political Science, and many other top CSSCI journals. He serves as an editor for Journal of Chinese Political Science. Sujian Guo (Ph.D. degree in political science), an honorary professor of the Fudan Institute for Advanced Study in Social Sciences; Principal Investigator of Fudan IAS Global Justice Index, Professor of Political Science and Director of the Center for US–China Policy Studies at San Francisco State University; former president of Association of Chinese Political Studies; Editor-in-Chief of the Journal of Chinese Political Science, the Journal of Chinese Governance, the Fudan Journal of the Humanities and Social Sciences, and the Chinese Political Science Review; Editor-in-Chief of Rowman & Littlefield-Lexington’s book series “Challenges Facing Chinese Political Development,” and Editor-in-Chief of Shanghai People’s Press book series of “China in Transition.” His research areas include comparative politics and Chinese politics, com- parative political economy, Sino-US relations, sustainable energy and environment, democratic transition, and economic transition. He has published more than 60 academic articles, and authored and edited over 35 books, including Palgrave Handbook on Local Governance in Contemporary China, Governance in Tran- sitional China; Political Science and Chinese Political Studies—The State of Field, The Political Economy of China’s Great Transformation; Global Sustainable Energy Competitiveness Report; Democratic Transi- tions: Modes and Outcomes; Chinese Politics and Government: Power, Ideology and Organization; The Political Economy of Asian Transition from Communism; Post-Mao China, among others. Global Justice Index Report Abstract 1 Introduction 2 Methodology: Construction of the Global Justice Index 2.1 First Step: Convert Indicator Indices 2.2 Second Step: Population-Based Weighting 2.3 Third Step: Calculate the Scores of Both Dimension Indices and Category Indices 2.4 Fourth Step: Calculate the Score of the Issue Index 2.5 Last Step: Calculate Global Justice Index 3 Findings 3.1 Issue 1: Climate Change 3.1.1 Dimensions and Indicators 3.1.2 Results 3.2 Issue 2: Peacekeeping 3.3 Dimensions and Indicators 3.3.1 Results 3.4 Issue 3: Humanitarian Aid 3.4.1 Indicators 3.4.2 Results 3.5 Issue 4: Terrorism and Armed Conflicts 3.5.1 Dimensions and Indicators 3.5.2 Results 3.6 Issue 5: Cross-National Criminal Police Cooperation 3.6.1 Dimensions and Indicators 3.7 Issue 6: Anti-poverty 3.7.1 Dimensions and Indicators 3.7.2 Results 3.8 Issue 7: Education 3.8.1 Dimensions and Indicators 3.8.2 Results 3.9 Issue 8: Public Health 3.9.1 Dimensions and Indicators 3.9.2 Results 3.10 Issue 9: Protection of Women and Children 3.10.1 Dimensions and Indicators 3.10.2 Results 3.11 Global Justice Index: Our Main Results 4 Conclusion Acknowledgements References work_73kq3wa55bhivcdjpk4blat2le ---- 398 398..399 A Swedish national database study concluded that mortality risks were highest in those untreated with antipsychotics. 4 However, this conclusion maybe an oversimplification and we suggest ‘untreated’ here describes being poorly engaged, lacking care and support rather than simply ‘untreated with antipsychotics’; indeed, ‘treated with antipsychotics’ could be a proxy for well engaged, supported and receiving a range of inter- ventions comparable to those recommended by NICE. Another anomaly was the study’s reported average age of 36 years for its FEP subgroup, much older than usually reported.5 Thus the study may have missed substantial numbers of younger people, a particularly vulnerable group for antipsychotic-induced weight gain and metabolic disturbance, limiting its applicability to more typically aged FEP populations.6 Nevertheless the finding that lower mortality correlated with low and moderate antipsychotic dosing supports the importance of good prescribing. Our simple collective view in providing this editorial as general practitioner, nurse and psychiatrist together, is that health inequality could be reduced by healthcare systems collaboratively embracing a more preventive approach in relation to the physical health of this vulnerable group from the earliest opportunity. 1 Mitchell AJ, De Hert M. Promotion of physical health in persons with schizophrenia: can we prevent cardiometabolic problems before they begin? Acta Psychiatr Scand 2015; 132: 83–5. 2 Barnes TR. Evidence-based guidelines for the pharmacological treatment of schizophrenia: recommendations from the British Association for Psychopharmacology. J Psychopharmacol 2011; 25: 567–620. 3 Dixon LB, Stroup ST. Medications for first-episode psychosis: making a good start. Am J Psychiatry 2015; 172: 209–11. 4 Tiihonen J, Mittendorfer-Rutz E, Torniainen M, Alexanderson K, Tanskanen A. Mortality and cumulative exposure to antipsychotics, antidepressants, and benzodiazepines in patients with schizophrenia: an observational follow-up study. Am J Psychiatry 7 Dec 2015 (doi: 10.1176/appi.ajp.2015.15050618). 5 Kirkbride JB, Fearon P, Morgan C, Dazzan P, Morgan K, Tarrant J, et al. Heterogeneity in incidence rates of schizophrenia and other psychotic syndromes: findings from the 3-center AeSOP study. Arch Gen Psychiatry 2006; 63: 250–8. 6 Correll CU, Manu P, Olshanskiy V, Napolitano B, Kane JM, Malhotra AK. Cardiometabolic risk of second-generation antipsychotic medications during first-time use in children and adolescents. JAMA 2009; 302: 1765–73. David Shiers, MBChB, MRCGP, MRCP(UK), School of Psychological Sciences, University of Manchester, Manchester M13 9PL, UK. Email: david.shiers@ doctors.org.uk; Jonathan Campion, MBBS, MRCPsych, South London and Maudsley NHS Foundation Trust, and Faculty of Brain Sciences, University College London, London; Tim Bradshaw, RMN, PhD, School of Nursing, Midwifery and Social Work, University of Manchester, Manchester, UK doi: 10.1192/bjp.208.4.398a ‘Lethal discrimination’, ideology and social justice Perhaps the journal risks accusations of hyperbole by adopting the slogan of ‘lethal discrimination’ in relation to the shockingly high standardised mortality ratios (SMRs) of people with severe mental illness (SMI). Other serious illnesses (cancer, etc.) have high SMRs but to suggest that this is due to lethal discrimination would attract criticism. Taggart & Bailey1 are right to draw attention to the high SMRs in people with SMI. This is consistent with accepted tenets of moral philosophy, particularly liberal political philosophy. Central to this are principles that citizens enjoy maximum liberty (subject to respect for the liberty of others) and, second, that social arrangements permit social inequality only to the degree that this improves the well-being of the least advantaged.2 People with SMI are among the most disadvantaged. Table 1 of the editorial indicates that those with SMI in contact with services fare better in the USA than in the UK. This will not surprise those who have expressed dismay about developments in mental health services in the UK. 3 However, the important question is whether the way US mental health services are funded, commissioned and managed may be better. Psychiatrists need to remain open minded about what systems deliver best results, if we are to achieve our aims effectively.4 International comparisons are notoriously difficult to make. A host of health and social indicators however suggest worse outcomes in more unequal societies. Because the USA is a more unequal society, Table 1 is counterintuitive. Perhaps Table 1 is misleading. Taggart & Bailey do not tell us whether the US data include outcomes of individuals with SMI receiving care in prison. In the past 40 years the proportion of people with SMI who are compulsorily detained in the USA has remained the same. However, whereas 40 years ago 75% were in mental hospitals and 25% in penal institutions, now the proportions are 5% and 95% respectively.5 Table 1 will have validity only if the outcomes of imprisoned individuals with SMI are included. Should further research confirm US superiority, another issue might arise: does more restrictive treatment (in prison) achieve better outcomes? If so, psychiatrists will have to face deeply uncomfortable questions. Could it be that enhanced incarceration leads to lesser freedom but a lower SMR? Would lower a SMR be the effect of more intensive psychopharmacological treatment or is there less psychopharmacological intervention in prison and the higher UK SMR is due to more psychopharmacological treatment in the community? What kind of societies lead to best outcomes for people with SMI? Health outcomes do not depend only on healthcare. To participate constructively in debate and action aimed at reducing SMRs in those with SMI, psychiatrists need to become familiar with the complex issues addressed by political philosophy2 as well as public mental health. They also need to be aware that although they may master evidence and political ethical reasoning, social ideology will sometimes prevail as to what happens on the ground.6 Perhaps it is anxiety secondary to this that impelled invention of the concept of lethal discrimination in people with SMI. Declaration of interest G.I. is an NHS consultant psychiatrist, and Chairman and Director, London International Practice Ltd. 1 Taggart H, Bailey S. Ending lethal discrimination against people with serious mental illness. Br J Psychiatry 2015; 207: 469–70. 2 Ikkos G. Fairness, liberty and psychiatry. Int Psychiatry 2009; 6: 46–8. 3 St John-Smith P, McQueen D, Michael A, Ikkos G, Denman C, Maier M, et al. The trouble with NHS psychiatry in England. Psychiatr Bull 2009; 33: 219–25. 4 Ikkos G, Sugarman P, Bouras N. Mental health services commissioning and provision: lessons from the UK? Psychiatriki 2015; 26: 181–7. 5 Bark N. Prisoner mental health in the USA. Int Psychiatry 2014; 11: 53–5. 6 Bouras N, Ikkos G. Ideology and psychiatry. Psychiatriki 2013; 24: 17–27. George Ikkos, Consultant Psychiatrist in Liaison Psychiatry, Royal National Orthopaedic Hospital NHS Trust, Stanmore, Middlesex, UK. Email: george.ikkos@ nhs.net doi: 10.1192/bjp.208.4.399 399 Correspondence Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:36, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core work_74aduhcbyvfddirxeybd24h3ka ---- wp-p1m-38.ebi.ac.uk Params is empty 404 sys_1000 exception wp-p1m-38.ebi.ac.uk no 221741191 Params is empty 221741191 exception Params is empty 2021/04/06-03:20:40 if (typeof jQuery === "undefined") document.write('[script type="text/javascript" src="/corehtml/pmc/jig/1.14.8/js/jig.min.js"][/script]'.replace(/\[/g,String.fromCharCode(60)).replace(/\]/g,String.fromCharCode(62))); // // // window.name="mainwindow"; .pmc-wm {background:transparent repeat-y top left;background-image:url(/corehtml/pmc/pmcgifs/wm-nobrand.png);background-size: auto, contain} .print-view{display:block} Page not available Reason: The web page address (URL) that you used may be incorrect. Message ID: 221741191 (wp-p1m-38.ebi.ac.uk) Time: 2021/04/06 03:20:40 If you need further help, please send an email to PMC. Include the information from the box above in your message. Otherwise, click on one of the following links to continue using PMC: Search the complete PMC archive. Browse the contents of a specific journal in PMC. Find a specific article by its citation (journal, date, volume, first page, author or article title). http://europepmc.org/abstract/MED/ work_74jcjm5y5ze47h6b6fbwd7jlmu ---- \\server05\productn\C\CPP\6-4\CPP402.txt unknown Seq: 1 16-OCT-07 12:55 ENCOURAGE RESTORATIVE JUSTICE JOHN BRAITHWAITE Australian National University At the 2000 United Nations (U.N.) Congress on the Prevention of Crime and Treatment of Offenders, many were surprised that a resolution for all nations to encourage restorative justice passed unanimously. Restorative justice comprises the idea that because crime hurts, justice should heal, and especially heal relationships. It is a process in which all stakeholders have an opportunity to discuss the hurts of a crime, how they might be repaired, how recurrence might be prevented, and how other needs of stakeholders can be met. Even the societies with the highest imprisonment rates in the world—the United States, Russia, and South Africa—and most executions—China—have been sites of important innovations in restorative justice. Although most societies have many small programs (perhaps even thousands now in the United States; Bazemore and Schiff (2005) were able to list 773 programs for juveniles alone), and tens of thousands in China (Wong, 1999), mostly the support is rhetorical, not extending to the mainstreaming of restorative justice evident in New Zealand, Norway, and much of the German-speaking world. A surprisingly universal experience is that restorative justice has not proved politically unpopular. As Frank Cullen points out with rehabilitation (2007, this issue), politicians can be punitive in many respects but still support restorative justice because it makes sense to citizens, and because 80% to 99% of people report good experiences with it, whether they are victims, offenders, supporters, or attending police officers (Braithwaite, 2002; Poulson, 2003). Politicians are unafraid to vote for it at the U.N. and at home because when demands for law and order run amok, they can always say they do not mean for restorative justice to be used in “that” kind of case. Since leaders of all religions have tended to be supportive of restorative justice, seeing it as creating spaces where spiritual experience flourishes, the conservative side of politics at least learns to live with restorative justice. RESTORE A BIT OF DEMOCRACY One reason restorative justice is popular is that it hands a little piece of power back to the ordinary people. We have become such mass democra- cies that face-to-face meetings on important questions of governance only include the elite. Not only are New England town meetings a democratic form that is hard to translate to a mass society, but also most citizens do not want to participate in community meetings. Most citizens do want to VOLUME 6 NUMBER 4 2007 PP 689–696 R \\server05\productn\C\CPP\6-4\CPP402.txt unknown Seq: 2 16-OCT-07 12:55 690 BRAITHWAITE attend restorative justice conferences, however, when asked by a victim or offender to come along to support them. There is something humbling and ennobling about being asked to help someone in trouble; people tend to be honored to be chosen as a supporter. The personal touch makes it a little opportunity to salvage some democratic participation, and the evi- dence indicates that most people relish being able to participate (Braithwaite, 2002:45–55,130–134). The procedural justice findings, more- over, show this feature of “process control” by ordinary citizens engenders a sense of fairness (Tyler, 1990). The Western social science literature on procedural justice, trust build- ing through democratic engagement, and the contribution of restorative justice to all of this has bigger implications in societies recovering from violent conflict than for the West itself. The empirical experience of peace building has been that although democratic elections, national reconcilia- tion, and forgiveness are fundamental ingredients of sustainable peace, they cannot be rushed. The recent mistakes in places like East Timor have been giving postconflict societies an election quickly, and then getting out. We know now that electoral outcomes that do not share power and leave one faction totally in control will exclude ethnic minorities and are not conducive to sustainable peace. Nor do elections work where warlords bribe village heads to get their entire village to vote for their man. Another thing we have learned is that although the time is taken to get electoral institutions to take root, control over most criminal justice can be taken away from hated central police institutions, with their torture cham- bers and secret dossiers, and returned to villages. There are always surviv- als of traditional restorative justice practices in villages. These practices have their human rights worries, even if they are less than the abuses of the wartime state. Ali Wardak (2004) has shown how traditional male- dominated village justice might be balanced by an internationally funded female-dominated new central Human Rights Commission to educate vil- lage elders about involving women and respecting a new order of human rights. Although warlords blocked Wardak’s ideas in his homeland Afghanistan, other postconflict areas such as Bougainville have observed what locals regard as a meaningful form of democratic participation restored through local control over (restorative) criminal justice (Howley, 2002). Restorative justice then becomes much more than a better way of managing crime; it becomes a way to help village societies become more rights-respecting and to learn to become democratic. RESTORE VICTIMS When victims have an opportunity to actually participate in restorative justice, they benefit much more consistently (compared to controls) than \\server05\productn\C\CPP\6-4\CPP402.txt unknown Seq: 3 16-OCT-07 12:55 CRIMINOLOGY & PUBLIC POLICY 691 do offenders (Sherman and Strang, 2007:62–65). Yet victims who want restorative justice are demoralized when it fails to happen or when the offender refuses to attend the meeting (Strang, 2002). Angel (2005) found in an experiment that restorative justice benefits the victim’s mental health by reducing post-traumatic stress symptoms. Victims emerge from restora- tive justice with reduced fear and anger, increased forgiveness, and feel more satisfied. The victim has a stronger sense that his or her rights are respected and that justice was done compared to controls (Strang, 2002; Braithwaite, 2002:45–53). DELIVER COMMITMENT TO DO WHAT WORKS Criminology is making progress on what works. But justice systems are not good at motivating people to do what works. Police know that the best predictor of being a victim of burglary is having recently been burglarized (Pease, 1998:v). Getting burglary victims to act preventively on this is the hard part. Routinely, people are imprisoned because this seems politically safer than cheaper, more effective interventions. Restorative circles can invite experts to present the evidence to lay stakeholders. This can over- come the propensity to do the safe punitive thing in favor of effective pre- vention or rehabilitation. If the victim and other stakeholders in an assault sign an agreement for anger management and compensation (rather than imprisonment), then it can become politically safe for the system to fill fewer prison cells. A small number of restorative programs that steer high- end minority offenders away from prison has shown that restorative justice can motivate a politics of evidence-based, emotionally intelligent justice (Sherman, 2003) to supplant incarcerative justice (Bonta et al., 1998). A Canadian Ministry of Justice meta-analysis of evaluations of restora- tive justice with credible control groups was encouraging on many fronts (Latimer et al., 2001). Its biggest effect was that the implementation of agreements was 33% higher in restorative justice cases than in controls. We should not be surprised that a court order is less likely to be complied with than an agreement consensually signed by an offender, his mother, his girlfriend, and his victim even if the court order can be legally enforced by another court order! Family and close friends are more powerful regu- lators of behavior than are the police and the courts. So the largest promise of restorative justice is not that it is more directly effective than alternatives such as court or plea bargains. It is that evi- dence-based restorative justice is a superior delivery vehicle for interven- tions that work when compared with traditional criminal justice. As criminology discovers more ways of reducing crime at lower cost in dollars and injustice, restorative justice can deliver the bottom-up commitment to realize implementation. \\server05\productn\C\CPP\6-4\CPP402.txt unknown Seq: 4 16-OCT-07 12:55 692 BRAITHWAITE REDUCE CRIME DIRECTLY That said, the evidence has progressively become stronger that restora- tive justice in itself is directly effective in reducing criminal reoffense. Moreover, restorative justice is a learning tradition. In an update and tightening of the methodological criteria of the Latimer et al. (2001) meta- analysis, Bonta et al (2006) found the recidivism effect was notably higher for second generation post-1997 restorative justice programs. All meta- analyses suggest significant but only modest direct effects in reducing reof- fending. This result is what most restorative justice theorists predicted. Why would you expect the direct effects of interventions of an hour or two to be large? Actually, the most recent review by Sherman and Strang (2007) suggests that we were wrong in that the modest positive result over- all combines some very large positive effects, especially with violence, zero effects, and occasional negative effects when compared with controls. We do not yet understand the drivers of these big variations in success and failure. It is also with violence that we get some surprisingly huge healing effects. In the Canberra RISE experiments, 45% of court case victims wanted to harm their offenders, compared with 9% for victims who went to a restorative justice conference (Sherman and Strang, 2007:63). For property offenses, this difference more than halved. Restorative justice delivers more apologies to victims, and apologies they view as sincere, than do court cases. This difference is also particularly strong with vio- lence cases. Again, because it is with violence that we find the biggest effects, I suspect evidence-based criminology has a major contribution to make to how we can be more effective in peace building after war. INCREASE JUSTICE Criminology was born with too myopic a concern with preventing crime. Some healthy developments have balanced that in recent decades. The rise of victimology has helped us prioritize better recovery for victims. Most nations have moral equivalents to Rodney King, O.J. Simpson, Klan kill- ing and cover-up, the Japanese internment camps of World War II, and the contemporary diaspora of internment camps for Muslims alleged to be ter- rorists. Therefore, all nations’ justice systems should be evaluated in terms of how successful they are in affecting reconciliation within and between communities after cases that question discrimination and respect for rights. The restoration of a sense of justice and reintegration of communi- ties thus stands beside reintegration of victims and offenders as outcomes that should concern criminologists. The social psychology of procedural justice is another recent tradition that adds a set of facets—consistency, \\server05\productn\C\CPP\6-4\CPP402.txt unknown Seq: 5 16-OCT-07 12:55 CRIMINOLOGY & PUBLIC POLICY 693 decision accuracy, correctability, process control, impartiality, and ethical- ity (Lind and Tyler, 1988)—in terms of which the “justice” in “justice sys- tems” is evaluated. The criminological community working on restorative justice, commu- nity justice, and cognate innovations deserves credit for being theoretically serious, nondogmatic, and plural. This effort has led them to be evidence- based and remarkably assiduous in a short space of years in generating a large body of outcome evaluation that explores the entire range of dimen- sions mentioned above. Moreover, so far restorative justice has fared well against these tests (for a now out-of-date survey, see Braithwaite, 2002). The restorative justice research tradition has advanced criminology’s nor- mative conversation on how justice should be defined, and its explanatory conversation on what responses to crime do best in promoting justice for victims, offenders, families of offenders, and other stakeholders. Justice can be conceived in a republican way (Braithwaite and Pettit, 1990). The evidence suggests what is good for republican justice is good for crime control and for democracy (when democracy is conceived in a civic republican way as contestatory and deliberative democracy, as opposed to the rule of opinion polls (Pettit (1997)). This combination of normative and empirical conclusions runs against the intuitions of many who view justice, rights, and democracy as obstacles to crime control. Yet the restorative justice literature is increasingly compelling that we can get less crime through more justice and more democracy. One of the shocking things about law school debate on justice is the assumption that justice ordered is justice delivered. Criminologists from many jurisdictions have always known that one half or one third of all fines that are imposed are never collected (Sherman and Strang, 2007). Here is where the superior implementation certainty of restorative justice increases the consistency of justice as delivered. In addition, the Sherman and Strang (2007:4) review concludes that diverting cases to restorative justice at least doubles (and can quadruple) the proportion of offenses that actually go to justice. Just-deserts advocates of formal prosecution rather than of restorative justice ignore the realities of absconding, loss of files, and no shows of witnesses, which means surprisingly often the prosecution never happens. Attrition can even be a primary reality of prosecutorial justice in experiments (Sherman and Strang, 2007:82). Perhaps this is because some are allowed to abscond because they are innocent. Yet randomization should deliver equal numbers of innocents in control and experimental groups. Another important finding in this respect is Daly et al. (2005): that there is more “charging down” of sexual assaults that are prosecuted than sexual assaults that go to restorative justice conferences. The latter has particularly important implications for justice as victim vin- dication (see also McAlinden, 2007). \\server05\productn\C\CPP\6-4\CPP402.txt unknown Seq: 6 16-OCT-07 12:55 694 BRAITHWAITE NO PANACEA The evidence suggests that all justice interventions, including restorative justice, frequently fail with terrible consequences. If it is right that restora- tive justice is the best delivery vehicle for other interventions that work, then it can be applied to interventions that can repair the harm done by bad restorative justice itself. Moreover, responsive regulatory theory (Braithwaite, 2002) argues that restorative justice should be a presump- tively preferred option at the base of a regulatory pyramid. Such respon- sive justice pyramids cover the weaknesses of one strategy with the strengths of other strategies higher up the pyramid, including more deter- rent and incapacitative options. REFERENCES Angel, Caroline 2005 Crime victims meet their offenders: Testing the impact of restorative justice conferences on victims’ post-traumatic stress symptoms. Doctoral Dissertation. University of Pennsylvania. Bazemore, Gordon and Mara Schiff 2005 Juvenile Justice Reform and Restorative Justice. Portland, Ore.: Willan Publishing. Bonta, James, Jennifer Rooney, and Suzanne Wallace-Capretta 1998 Restorative Justice: An Evaluation of the Restorative Resolutions Project. Ottawa, Canada: Solicitor General Canada. Bonta, James, Rebecca Jesseman, Tanya Rugge, and Robert Cormier 2006 Restorative Justice and Recidivism: Promises Made, Promises Kept? In D. Sullivan and L. Tifft (eds.), Handbook of Restorative Justice: A Global Perspective. London: Routledge. Braithwaite, John 2002 Restorative Justice and Responsive Regulation. New York: Oxford University Press. Braithwaite, John and Philip Pettit 1990 Not Just Deserts: A Republican Theory of Criminal Justice. Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press. Cullen, Francis T. 2007 Make rehabilitation corrections’ guiding paradigm. Criminology & Public Policy. This issue. Daly, Kathleen, Brigitte Bouhours, Sarah Curtis-Fawley, Leanne Weber, and Rita Scholl 2005 South Australia Juvenile Justice and Criminal Justice (SAJJ-CJ) Technical Report No. 3: Sexual Assault Archival Study (SASS), An archival Study of Sexual Offence Cases Disposed of in Youth Court and by Conference and Formal Caution, 2d edition, revised and expanded. Brisbane, Queensland, Australia: School of Criminology and Criminal Justice, Griffith University. Available online; http://www.griffith.edu.au/school/ccj/ kdaly.html. \\server05\productn\C\CPP\6-4\CPP402.txt unknown Seq: 7 16-OCT-07 12:55 CRIMINOLOGY & PUBLIC POLICY 695 Howley, Patrick 2002 Breaking Spears and Mending Hearts. Sydney, Australia: Federation Press. Latimer, Jeff, Craig Dowden, and Danielle Muise 2001 The Effectiveness of Restorative Justice Practices: A Meta-Analysis. Ottawa, Canada: Department of Justice, Canada. Lind, E. Allan and Tom R. Tyler 1988 The Social Psychology of Procedural Justice. New York: Plenum Press. McAlinden, Anne-Marie 2007 The Shaming of Sexual Offenders: Risk, Retribution and Reintegration. Portland, Ore.: Hart Publishing. Pease, Ken 1998 Repeat Victimisation: Taking Stock. Police Research Group Crime Detection and Prevention Series Paper 90. London: Home Office. Pettit, Philip 1997 Republicanism. Oxford, U.K.: Clarendon Press. Poulson, Barton 2003 A third voice: A review of empirical research on the psychological outcomes of restorative justice. Utah Law Review 1:167–204. Sherman, Lawrence 2003 Reason for emotion: Reinventing justice with theories, innovations, and research. The American Society of Criminology, 2002 Presidential Address. Criminology 41:1–38. Sherman, Lawrence and Heather Strang 2007 Restorative Justice: The Evidence. London: The Smith Institute. Strang, Heather 2002 Repair or Revenge: Victims and Restorative Justice. Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press. Tyler, Tom 1990 Why People Obey the Law. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press. Wardak, Ali 2004 Building a post-war justice system in Afghanistan. Crime, Law and Social Change 41:319–341. Wong, Dennis 1999 Delinquency control and juvenile justice in China. Australian and New Zealand Journal of Criminology 32:27–41. John Braithwaite is a professor in the Regulatory Institutions Network, Australian National University. Regulatory, criminological, and peace-building theory are his abid- ing interests. His empirical work connects each of these realms of theory to domains usually occupied by the other two. His contributions to criminology have been on restorative justice, republican normative theory, and reintegrative shaming. These con- tributions have most recently been systematized and revised in E. Ahmed, N. Harris, J. \\server05\productn\C\CPP\6-4\CPP402.txt unknown Seq: 8 16-OCT-07 12:55 696 BRAITHWAITE Braithwaite, and V. Braithwaite, Shame Management Through Reintegration (Cam- bridge, 2001) and J. Braithwaite, Restorative Justice and Responsive Regulation (Oxford, 2002). work_75nrkubfpfdknfowe4757xebfi ---- Beyond Transitional Justice? JOURNAL FÜR ENTWICKLUNGSPOLITIK herausgegeben vom Mattersburger Kreis für Entwicklungspolitik an den österreichischen Universitäten vol. XXVII 3–2011 Beyond Transitional Justice Schwerpunktredaktion: Stefan Khittel Inhaltsverzeichnis 4 Stefan Khittel, Jan Pospisil Beyond Transitional Justice? 21 Sandra Rubli Knowing the Truth – What For? The Contested Politics of Transitional Justice in Burundi 43 Susanne Schmeidl The Quest for Transitional Justice in Afghanistan: Exploring the Untapped Potential of Customary Justice 64 Katja Seidel Practising Justice in Argentina: Social Condemnation, Legal Punishment, and the Local Articulations of Genocide 88 Christian Wlaschütz Transitional Justice in Colombia: Does it Contribute to Reconciliation? 109 Book Review 111 Editor of the Special Issue and Authors 114 Impressum  Stefan Khittel, Jan Pospisil Journal für Entwicklungspolitik XXVII 3-2011, S. 4-20 STEFAN KHITTEL, JAN POSPISIL Beyond Transitional Justice? 1. Introduction During the last decade, the term ‘transitional justice’ has become a kind of buzzword. It is extensively used within the UN system as well as within many International NGOs and national governments to describe a wide range of measures of how to deal with a violent past. Interestingly, the concept of transitional justice was coined and elaborated mainly outside the academic context. While closely linked to academic debates, many features of the concept are actually a result of developments in the field and on the political level. Moreover, during the last 20 years the meaning of transi- tional justice has been broadened, something made explicit by the Kofi Annan Report The rule of law and transitional justice in conflict and post-con- flict societies from 2004, where not only a variety of judicial, but also non- judicial mechanisms are proposed (Annan 2004). Hence, one of the first questions that arises is precisely whether there are any normative, institu- tional, psychosocial or social strategies that are not covered by the notion of transitional justice. One major problem of such an inclusive definition of transitional justice – not the least for academics – is that its analytical value is quite limited. This amorphous notion might be seen more as a proxy for an ambiguous and messy compilation of almost any measure, method or other approach of coping with massive violence in a country. If this is so, why bother using the concept at all? The answer, in short, is that such an influential concept employed by powerful organisations becomes itself – irony aside – a battlefield where meanings are constructed, imposed or sanctioned. Thus, looking at what the debates on transitional justice are and, even more importantly, at what lies beyond, becomes not only a formidable academic Beyond Transitional Justice? task but also necessarily an exercise in analysing political power. This latter assertion is exactly the opposite of what some proponents of transitional justice would espouse. With this volume we want to present a small but hopefully mean- ingful contribution to the discussion on transitional justice. Each contri- bution is based on extended periods of fieldwork and/or direct involvement in the processes – and problems – of transitional justice at the local level. Although the charge of a certain eclecticism can be levelled against this volume, nevertheless, the geographical range of the examples is fairly wide. More importantly, the topical coverage is broad. What is most important though, is that there is a common leitmotif linking the articles: namely, the question of what lies beyond the notion of transitional justice and how that can elucidate the processes of transitional justice. 2. The two histories of transitional justice Before discussing the main assumptions, approaches and contradic- tions inherent to transitional justice, it is certainly helpful to look at the history of the concept. The first major question that arises in this regard is probably that of how old the concept might really be. As with many other concepts from the multilateral or bilateral security and development policy context, transitional justice, much like other concepts such as Good Governance or Sustainability, seems to have been always there. Going by age, transitional justice can be considered as a young adult. The first explicit mention of the term dates back some 20 years, to the early to mid 1990s. While this seems to be a quite long time-span, espe- cially given the dynamics of the international policy discourse, it has to be taken into account that transitional justice at that time had a very different meaning compared to nowadays. In fact, it might even be advis- able to speak about two histories of transitional justice; histories that, on the one hand, share some important similarities, but, on the other, deal with different contexts and challenges. The 1990s history of transitional justice is intrinsically linked not only to the fall of the Iron Curtain and the democratisation processes in Eastern Europe, but also to the end of military dictatorships in Latin America and  Stefan Khittel, Jan Pospisil Asia. During the 1980s, the US policy apparatus developed the concept of ‘democracy promotion’ as one of its main approaches in foreign affairs (cf. Robinson 1996: 73ff ) The democratic transitions in Argentine and Chile became the first test cases on the American continent and, via instru- ments like truth commissions, also the first occasions when the demo- cratic transition became linked to the concept of transitional justice (cf. Stotzky 1993: 187ff ). Of course, the Nuremberg Trials, which held accountable leading figures from Nazi Germany after their defeat in World War II, served as the key background against which these new processes unfolded (cf. Teitel 2002: 373). Mainly relevant in that regard was, as Thomas Carothers (2002) has called it, the ‘transition paradigm’: the process of (re-)democ- ratisation in the sense of the denazification (historically) or demilitarisa- tion (in Latin America) of domestic politics through the instruments of the judiciary. It was in the early 1990s that these processes of transitional justice in Latin America were linked to the transition processes in Eastern Europe. Neil Kritz (1995: xxix) for example recalls a conference in Salzburg, Austria, in March 1992, where politicians, journalists and other members of the civil society from Latin America (e.g. Uruguay, Argentine) and Eastern Europe (Hungary, Bulgaria, Lithuania, Czechoslovakia) met to discuss how “to cope with the legacy of that ousted system” (ibid.). It was one of the first occasions when contemporary problems of tran- sitional justice – who is to be seen as a victim, or what to do with the mass of ‘little’ perpetrators – were addressed and systematically discussed. Addi- tionally, questions about the financing and the internationalisation of such processes came into play. It is not by chance that the publication of Kritz’s three volumes on Transitional Justice from 1995, based on research results from a multi-year project on transition processes at the US Institute for Peace, was the first occasion when the term was explicitly mentioned in the scientific discourse in a more prominent way. While the focus on democratic transitions in Latin America and Eastern Europe was rather straightforward, the inclusion of the then-rele- vant case of Ethiopia (after the fall of the Mengistu-regime, cf. Kritz 1995: xxxvi) already offered a case were such a transition was not so clear-cut. At first, in the heyday of the democracy promotion paradigm, cases like Ethi- Beyond Transitional Justice? opia were understood in the context of democratic transition. As Carothers critically points out, by the end of the 1990s nearly 100 countries world- wide were defined within the transition label by US policy actors – what Carothers sees as a sign that “the transition paradigm has outlived its usefulness” (Carothers 2002: 6). In foreign policy terms, particularly regarding the United States, Carothers’ statement might be right or wrong – it proved to be irrelevant in any case, since the promotion of democracy, with the primary test cases of Afghanistan and Iraq and a renewed focus on this since the onset of the Obama presidency, with its focus on ‘fragile democracies’, has remained a highly relevant raison d’être for international (military as well as civilian) interventions from the early 2000s until now. Nevertheless, the de-linking of the concept from the democratic tran- sition context was the start of the second history of transitional justice. In that regard, the genocide in Rwanda acted as the main watershed, since it confronted the concept with unforeseen and in fact unimaginable chal- lenges. It was not primarily the number of victims and the inconceivable cruelties of the event, rather, it was the high number of perpetrators (tens of thousands of people, a significant part of the post-genocide population in the country), together with a completely depleted political and in fact non-existent juridical system that caused the difficulties. While Nuremberg also played an important part as a historical prece- dent in this case (although not mainly in terms of denazification, but more because of its way of dealing with the crime of genocide), it was obvious that the sheer number not only of murders, but especially of immediate perpetrators of acts of concrete violence, called for new approaches in dealing with the potential judicial consequences. At that point, transitional justice comes into play as a process not (or at least not only) for dealing with the judicial consequences of a process of democratisation, but mainly as a way of elaborating and linking the various avenues in the post-conflict transition from war to peace, with its main focus on perpetrators of mass violence in often internal and asymmetric civil wars on the periphery. This shift had two important consequences for the concept: firstly, it was opened to other forms or systems of justice that promised at least the possibility of dealing with the huge number of perpe- trators (and the complex intertwining between perpetration and victim-  Stefan Khittel, Jan Pospisil hood in many situations) in a more pragmatic way. In particular, it was Rwanda and the remarkable success of the so called Gacaca courts which paved the way for the integration of Traditional Justice mechanisms into the realm of transitional justice. Secondly, the question of financing and internationalisation came back on the agenda since from Rwanda onwards the main focal points of Traditional Justice were moved from comparably rich regions of soon- to-be EU-members in Eastern Europe and the more successful economies in South America to poor countries in so-called underdeveloped regions, often devastated by long periods of warfare or violent conflict. Conse- quently, transitional justice became one of the main sectors of interna- tional development cooperation with such countries, alongside related challenges like Disarmament, Reintegration, Security Sector Reform and wider measures in the context of ‘Rule of Law’. Transitional justice’s inclu- sion as part of the donor agenda has had important consequences for its content, approaches and vision, as we will show in the discussion of some of its main contradictions below, and as some of the papers will demon- strate with specific case studies. Today’s most relevant definition of transitional justice was delivered by UN’s Secretary General Kofi Annan in his report The rule of law and transitional justice in conflict and post-conflict societies in 2004. Here, transi- tional justice is explicitly placed in the context of peace and state building interventions in a post-conflict setting. Its aim therefore is to deal with the “legacy of large-scale past abuses, in order to ensure accountability, serve justice and achieve reconciliation” (Annan 2004: paragraph 8). The measures and methods proposed clearly demonstrate the evolution of the concept beyond the democratic transition context; thus, not only judicial, but also “non-judicial mechanisms” are to be included, “with differing levels of international involvement (or none at all) and individual pros- ecutions, reparations, truth-seeking, institutional reform, vetting and dismissals, or a combination thereof ” (ibid.). Annan’s overview indeed highlights all relevant focal points of contem- porary discussions of transitional justice as a concept and the implications it already has, should have or should not have. In particular, there are three critical challenges and contradictions – also shown by the contribu- tions in this volume – that demand further discussion: the relationship of Beyond Transitional Justice? justice, truth seeking and peace building; the, as Annan has called it, level of international involvement, in particular in its relation to traditional justice, but also in regard to the current rise of international criminal law; and the question of reparation, especially in its relation to the question of victimhood, personal as well as structural. 3. What about truth? And justice? And peace? From the 1970s on, but mainly during the 1980s and 1990s, especially in Latin America, the so-called truth commissions were all the rage in transitional democracies. Today, they number more than 40. In hindsight, one safely assumes with the Annan Report that truth commissions could now be considered part of a transitional justice programme. The simple fact stated there is that “[i]t is now generally recognized, for example, that truth commissions can positively complement criminal tribunals, as the examples of Argentina, Peru, Timor-Leste and Sierra Leone suggest” (Annan 2004: paragraph 26). However, this was not always the case, as truth commissions were held to be only second best options as compared to actual prosecutions (cf. Kaiser-Whande/Schell-Faucon 2008: 11). Nevertheless, since Uganda 1974 truth commissions have had a respectable career as tools in reconcilia- tion processes, engaging closely with society. These truth commissions are working more on the level of reparative and restorative justice than on the level of (penal) retribution. Surprisingly, and in spite of being heralded as a self-evident tool for overcoming civil strife or mass atrocities, there has not been much empir- ical evidence of the importance of truth-commissions for furthering the peace processes (cf. Fletcher et al. 2009). Mendeloff elaborates 17 assump- tions inherent in the reasoning of defenders of institutional truth telling and truth seeking (Mendeloff 2004: 364). Coincidentally, it can be argued that these claims sum up most assumptions of liberal peacebuilding. For convenience broken down into three groups (Psychological, Identity, and Institutional and Normative assumptions), they constitute the core claims of any truth-seeking, truth-telling mechanism. After dismantling or dismissing all of them, Mendeloff concludes that there might still be  Stefan Khittel, Jan Pospisil some value for peacebuilding in truth commissions, although such value is likely to be overestimated. It is then hardly astonishing that when examining handbooks dealing with peace or conflict resolution, the term transitional justice hardly shows up. Neither the Handbook of Peace and Conflict Studies (Webel/Galtung 2007) nor the Handbook of Conflict Analysis and Resolution (Sandole et al. 2009) contain a chapter on transitional justice, but what is even more signif- icant, is that not even the indexes of these books give any reference to this concept. The only exception is The SAGE Handbook of Conflict Resolution that features one single article on Peace vs. Justice – and Beyond (Albin 2009), where the concept of transitional justice makes it into a short chapter. 4. Levels of justice – levels of involvement Since its first use – in fact dating back to the Nuremberg trials – tran- sitional justice has been characterised by a sometimes complex interplay of different levels. This is not least due to one of the main rationales behind transitional justice: that it comes, or has to come into, play if or when the national systems of justice are overwhelmed by the scale of violations (cf. Simpson 2008: 74). It was also after Nuremburg, but at the latest during the emergence of the international ad-hoc-tribunals in the 1980s that such powerlessness was not only interpreted in a quantitative way, but also qual- itatively, in the sense that a national justice system might not be willing to prosecute mass scale perpetrators, mainly for political reasons. Following this line of argument, international involvement seems to be a logical step. Such a step could and should assist the national and the local levels in multiple ways, like offering neutral localities where courts and tribunals could be established, by bringing in neutral judges as well as legal expertise, or by offering financial assistance, thus significantly lowering the national costs of any process of transitional justice. Such technical support seems to be rather self-evident and unanimously supported and it would probably be perceived that way if it limited itself to only this technical dimension. However, like most other forms of tech- nical support on an international level, such self-limitation remains a delu- sion. We have to take into account here that most processes of transitional Beyond Transitional Justice? justice in the past two decades have taken place in so-called development countries, thus placing international support for such processes within a donor-recipient-relationship. It particularly because of this relationship that the interplay between the various levels – the local, the national, the inter- national – becomes not only complex, but also complicated. Furthermore, there is a truly global dimension to this internationa- li sa tion of transitional justice, connected to what Ruti G. Teitel (2002: 360) has called a new “humanitarian regime” against the background of a “global rule of law” that “both enables and restrains power in today’s political circumstances in order to manage new conditions of political disorder through the rubric of law” (ibid.: 371). Such management, along with the transformation of the international order since the end of the Cold War, now no longer stops at state borders but instead demonstrates a “heightened enforcement of the expanded norms, which are directed beyond states to persons and peoples” (ibid.: 363). Transitional justice thus becomes an integral part of a ‘global rule of law’ regime that is transforming the much older global regime of Human Rights into a more concrete, interventionist endeavour. Consequently, this new global rule of law regime goes along with the creation of various levels of international institutions that “range from the international courts to nongovernmental organizations” (ibid.: 363). These new groups of actors are designed to constitute and execute a global regime, but – and this is their most important feature regarding transitional justice – they are executing it in most cases not on a global level, but rather negotiate and implement it on the local and national levels. Such transformed implementation of a global regime on a local level by international institutions, partly on their own, partly via the funding and guiding of local and national institutions, carries various risks. Of these, the main problem might be what we call the ‘double simplification’ of internationally implemented processes of transitional justice. The first process of simplification is mainly due to the international/ local divide and the inevitable particular interests of the respective institu- tions. For example, the intervention of the International Criminal Court (ICC) in Uganda – the case against the leadership of the Lord’s Resistance Army (LR A) – became a highly contested issue since it interfered with regional attempts to start a peace process between the Ugandan Govern-  Stefan Khittel, Jan Pospisil ment and the LRA. As a consequence, various concerns and criticisms of the court were raised (cf. Allen 2006: 96ff ). Such local criticism soon became an international problem and a serious concern for the court, since it was its first high profile case and was initially regarded as quite uncontroversial. Therefore, stepping back was not an option, and Chief Prosecutor Moreno- Ocampo got engaged in a highly political debate, not only about the crimes of the LRA, but also about their (according to him, non-existent) political agenda and the prospects of peace talks. Besides the obvious problem that the Chief Prosecutor had now become practically associated with the ICC as a whole in the public debate in Uganda, Moreno-Ocampo was in no way, either through his position or his exper- tise, able and/or qualified to seriously comment on such issues. His political interventions hence proved to be counterproductive, not only for the situa- tion on the ground, but also for the ICC itself –because of the simplifying and, for the informed public, sometimes embarrassing statements but also because of the fact that, against this background, the potential war crimes of the Ugandan government in their fight against the LRA (but also in the course of their interventions in the DRC) became neglected in the juridical debate. Later, the court tried to correct this mistake with extensive outreach programs to the communities in Northern Uganda. Secondly, the specific discourse of criminal law was also designed to present a simple rationale. What is a general feature of criminal law, and of the main arguments of criminal law experts in their calls for the self- restraint of the discipline, takes on a special flavour when combined with the global rule of law regime and the complexity of conflict or post-con- flict situations. “The discourse of global criminal law that informs ICC interventions embodies a specific epistemology that interprets situations of violence through certain categories – namely, the criminal, the victim, and the transcendent judge” (Branch 2007: 190). Obviously, the room for manoeuvre in terms of political negotiation processes turns out to be rather slim when applying such categories to the various actors. This not always proves to be detrimental though, given that groups accused of such crimes might indeed change their behaviour in order to get back to (or at least increase their chances of ) negotiations. Nevertheless, such a strict criminal-victim divide is of course unable to deal comprehensively with processes of mass violence. The re-disco- Beyond Transitional Justice? vering of the local in the context of peace-building in the mid 1990s (cf. Mac Ginty 2008: 140) offered a potentially rewarding road to follow by including traditional methods of justice and reconciliation in processes of transitional justice. The above-mentioned Gacaca courts in Rwanda proved to be remarkably successful in this regard, thus leading to the increased popularity of traditional justice, particularly within the donor community. Nevertheless, the problems of simplification also remain significant in that regard, as Tim Allen (2006: 138ff ) showed in the case of the perceptions of traditional justice methods (the so called Mato Oput in Northern Uganda, cf. also Buckley-Zistel 2010: 113) and the attempts of achieving an interna- tional criminal prosecution of the LRA leadership. The perceptions and also the expectations of the people living in the area were mixed and showed no clear preferences whatsoever. Nevertheless, traditional justice at times was offered as the panacea of transitional justice by sections of the donor and NGO community, a phenomenon that Roger Mac Ginty (2008: 142) has explained by referring to a certain shared interest of the actors involved: “At a superficial level, this ‘popularity’ may reflect a prosaic and mutually beneficial relationship between local and international actors: the former may be motivated by a desire to secure any resources and kudos the latter can offer, while the latter may regard traditional and indigenous actors as a means of achieving donor- driven conditions on local participation and acceptance.” Such aspects show that the various levels of transitional justice are in no way coherent or complementary from the outset. Any international involve- ment leads to severe problems, on the ground as well as on the structural level, while on the other hand the local level in most cases is simply unable to deal with the challenges that accompany any post-conflict-situation. Hence, conclusions are difficult to draw, and the call for self-restraint, in particular in the case of international actors, might be the only option possible. Any process of transitional justice will consist of negotiations between different groups of actors, acting on different levels. A pragmatic approach seems to be the best way to move forward in that regard, notwithstanding the fact that such a “pragmatic approach (often embedded in negotiated processes) is testing the boundaries of how much justice is enough to satisfy the obliga- tions of international law” (Simpson 2008: 79).  Stefan Khittel, Jan Pospisil 5. Reparation and victimhood A central theme running through all forms of transitional justice is the reparation for victims of mass atrocities, war crimes, and human rights violations in general. These reparations are awarded in varying modes, but these modes share one condition: they are given to victims. Victimhood is thus ontologised. It is also elevated onto a moral pedestal. The construction of victimhood, especially beyond the individual case, becomes a political power game, both on the side of national and international actors. Interestingly, there have been changes in perspective during the last decades. Meister (2002) illustrates this by analysing a major change in the definition of a perpetrator and a victim for the period of the Cold War and after. During the Cold War many revolutionary groups resorted to violence as the only promising means of gaining political power and deemed this choice of method as just, as a “weapon of the weak” (ibid.: 92). After the transition to democracy and especially after 9/11 all political violence is called terrorist and terrorism becomes a bad thing in itself and has to be prosecuted. The ‘good terrorist’ has irrevocably become an oxymoron. The victim in the 21st century has to be an innocent victim. While individualising guilt has grown into a major concern for inter- national courts dealing with violent pasts, such as the ICTY and the ICC (cf. Leebaw 2008), victimhood has become a lump category for all who have lost their lives, families, homes. Unsurprisingly, the problems that arise from both lumping together all sorts of victims and at the same time insisting on the innocence of these victims can turn into a mission that is hardly manageable. Not only is the line between the perpetrator and victim in many cases a thin one – forcibly recruited child soldiers are a prime example – but the changing political climate may change the perspec- tive on a violent conflict (see above) and thus alter the meaning of perpe- trator and victim completely. Additionally, the category of gender has only recently received closer attention (cf. Buckley-Zistel/Oettler 2011). Moreover, there can be parallel processes of reparation that possibly overlap in intricate ways. To give just one example that is also included in this collection of articles, though from another point of view, let us consider Colombia. In that country, many laws for the reparation of victims have been passed, the most inclusive just recently (in June 2011, cf. Wlaschütz Beyond Transitional Justice? this issue). However, these reparations deal with the injustices of the last two decades at most. Nevertheless, there has been a parallel effort for the reparation for African Colombians to compensate for their historic enslave- ment (cf. Mosquera 2007). Because of the historical nature of slavery there can be no penal component to this process, but reparative justice meas- ures are heatedly discussed. Unfortunately, for the defenders of reparative measures, the categories get fuzzy. One obvious reason is the historical distance and the fact that no direct survivors of slavery are still alive. The demographic process has lead to complicated identities and the question of who is African Colombian is far from banal. Indeed, it is the locus of academic as well as political disputes (cf. Arocha 2005). The portion of African Colombians varies from around one per cent to up to fifty per cent. Even if these two numbers are extremes, they illustrate well the difficulty of reaching a workable definition of ‘Africanness’ for an eventual reparation. To complicate matters even more, the historical claims of African Colombians also compete with the historical claims of the indigenous populations. The land issue in particular is a thorny one, and this despite the existing regulations that try to do justice to the rural populace of both sides; consequently, two collective identities are pitted against each other in the name of victimhood and the various claims this entails. As Díaz (2010: 300ff ) rightly points out, African Colombians have suffered disproportionately from the violent civil conflict of the last decades. They have been made a priority for sped up reparation by national courts precisely because of their historical subjugation. Claudia Mosquera (2007) takes the same line when she argues that African Colombians have to receive reparations both for being ‘rescued’ from enslavement and having been ‘forcibly displaced’ during the war. The challenging diffi- culties of defining who is African Colombian aside, a central problem is that African Colombians also acted on the side of the perpetrators. This is patently clear in the case of the ongoing armed conflict, but it is also true for the historical example. Sergio Mosquera (1997) shows that, although Africans freed themselves by various means such as buying their freedom from their master or running away, when free some resorted to the use of slave labour themselves.  Stefan Khittel, Jan Pospisil 6. Preview of papers The four articles compiled in this issue deal with the phenomenon of transitional justice from different angles. Though some problems such as the contested political nature of all cases come up more than once, the focus of each text is different, just as each country has a particular history of violent conflict. Another issue surfacing in every text is truth: truth as an indispensable ingredient to reach justice and at the same time its role at the centre of political dispute. The papers also have in common a perspec- tive that extends beyond transitional justice in the normative sense. This new perspective is precisely how this notion – which has degenerated into a buzzword – can reclaim analytical meaning and may once again be a valuable concept and tool for dealing with atrocities. Sandra Rubli’s article, empirically based on her research in Burundi, proceeds to tell the intricate history of conflict in Burundi and the deal- ings with the violent past there. The case of Burundi could make a neat example of transitional justice were it not for the controversies surrounding this process. Truth is not a neutral matter when political parties compete for power, especially if these parties are all involved in one way or another with past violence. The notion is that whoever wins the power over truth wins political power or, conversely, whoever holds political power avoids dealing with certain aspects of truth about the past in order not to endanger their position. Any international intervention can then be perceived as meddling with national or local politics and will be challenged in one way or another. Even an internationally brokered accord like the Arusha Peace and Reconciliation Agreement that was signed by parties of the earlier conflict in Burundi has not been implemented, except for minor measures. This might be due to the fact that not all parties concerned were included in the process and thus were reluctant to accede to the Agreement. On the other hand, all parties see different opportunities in the workings of transitional justice and try to influence the process to their advantage. The conclusion is, that in order to ensure that transitional justice can work reasonably well, one has to understand the concerns, motivations, interests and intentions of all the parties (in the broad sense) involved. Otherwise, such a process is doomed to fail. Beyond Transitional Justice? The contribution written by Susanne Schmeidl sheds light on the case of customary justice in Afghanistan. Despite the fact that Afghanistan features prominently in many academic and political analyses and that the opera- tion of transitional justice there is at the centre of attention of the UN, the rigour of the political situation has dealt harsh blows to many core aspects of transitional justice as laid out by the UN system. Instead of truth for everybody, reparation for the victims and punishment for the wrongdoers, amnesty laws without accompanying mechanisms to reveal the truth have been passed by the national government in order to gain political leverage. Earlier attempts to establish justice and reconciliation also failed miserably because of the meddling of local politicians. It may seem an ironic twist when Schmeidl then advocates locally based customary justice practices as a new approach for transitional justice. She argues that customary justice institutions have shown persistence and acces- sibility and so she, instead, focuses on restorative, not retributive, justice. The latter may also be interpreted as a lack of effective enforcement of legal decisions by customary law institutions, but nonetheless this does not equate to impunity. The perpetrators usually have to ask the victims’ fami- lies for forgiveness and in many cases have to pay ‘blood-money’. However, customary law is not a panacea. There are problems, for instance the fact that the community cohesion must be strong enough in order to resist tensions arising from the processes and judgments. Another problem is the gender bias within traditional institutions. Women tend to be excluded or discrimi- nated against. Finally, the cases may be too many for the traditional system to handle, especially because some of the institutions have already other obligations they must cope with. Schmeidl concludes positively, arguing that such a view, beyond the beaten track of transitional justice practices that have not met with impressive success, might offer new directions of how to overcome a difficult impasse. Katja Seidel describes local practices of justice in Argentina, one of the classic examples of a democracy in transition. Within a few years after the end of the dictatorship, the country had a tribunal and also a Truth Commis- sion that dealt with the horrors of the military dictatorship. A legal frame- work that effectively barred attorneys from prosecuting the perpetrators of human rights violations was set up not much later. Despite the fact that the law made it difficult for the national legal system to act against perpetra-  Stefan Khittel, Jan Pospisil tors, a local practice called ‘escrache’ developed into an instrument of estab- lishing justice. This exercise is not backed by the state but is anchored in local community practices that not only ‘pillory’ the culprit but also bring about a consolidation of the community. Again, truth in this context is broken down to very specific individuals, local contexts and histories. The National Commission has no more authority in this particular form of action. Quite from the opposite side on the spectrum of legal systems comes an initiative that seeks to establish the atrocities committed during the era of the military dictatorship as genocide. From this it could follow that national legal provisions that protect perpetrators from further prosecu- tion could be undermined by International Law. Here again, local interests enter the political arena and a transitional justice process that had appar- ently ended is re-opened and re-negotiated. The contestation in the Argen- tinean case comes thus from both the local and the international level. Finally, Christian Wlaschütz’s article is on Colombia. Despite the fact that both countries are located on the same continent, the cases of Argen- tina and Colombia are quite divergent. Contrary to Argentina, the conflict in Colombia is still ongoing and agreements between parties have only been partial until now. This feature hardly makes it a role model for transitional justice. There has never been a truth commission or a practice comparable to ‘escrache’ but rather court hearings for the penitent wrongdoers so that they can receive a remission or reduction of a prison sentence. The word ‘genocide’ has not been frequently used for the Colombian case and would probably not fit the complex history of armed conflict in that country. The problem that Wlaschütz poses himself is whether transitional justice can contribute anything to a process of reconciliation between victims and perpetrators. His contention is that there is already enough truth around; in other words, it is well known who committed which crimes. However, there is also a lack of political will at the higher echelons of national politics to acknowledge crimes against humanity, mistakes, or even blunders by the official armed forces. The author, in general, detects a certain deficiency in the application of measures against perpetrators. Ironically, the most severe punishments against the political leaders of the paramilitary forces have been imposed on them by the US legal system, albeit for drug crimes barely related to the grave crimes against humanity which are of concern in the Colombian processes. Beyond Transitional Justice? The cases of Burundi and Colombia also show the difficulties of complex, multiparty peace processes after at least partial agreements have been reached. Argentina and Afghanistan are starting to open an expressly local perspective for transitional justice while at the same time being firmly embedded in the international context. Then there is the ethnic dimension of the population in Burundi as well as in Afghanistan. These intersecting themes open another aspect for possible comparisons and debates among scholars of transitional justice, something that cannot be explored here but which seems a promising option. References Albin, Cecilia (2009): Peace vs. Justice – and Beyond. In: Bercovitch, Jacob/ Kremenyuk, Víctor/Zartmann, I. William (eds.): The SAGE Handbook of Conflict Resolution. London: Sage, 580-594. Allen, Tim (2006): Trial Justice: The International Criminal Court and the Lord’s Resistance Army. London: Zed Books. Annan, Kofi (2004): The rule of law and transitional justice in conflict and post- conflict societies. Report of the Secretary-General, S/2004/616. New York: United Nations. Arocha, Jaime (2005): Afro-Colombia en los años post-Durban. In: Palimpsesto 5, 26-41. Branch, Adam (2007): Uganda’s Civil War and the Politics of ICC Intervention. In: Ethics and International Affairs 21 (2), 179-198. Buckley-Zistel, Susanne (2010): Globale Rechtsprechung, lokale Konflikt. Der Inter- nationale Strafgerichtshof als friedensstiftende Maßnahme in Uganda? In: Bonacker, Torsten/Daxner, Michael/Free, Jan H./Zürcher, Christoph (eds.): Interventionskulturen. Zur Soziologie der Interventionsgesellschaften. Wies- baden: VS Verlag, 101-118. Buckley-Zistel, Susanne/Oettler, Anika (2011): Was bedeutet Transitional Justice? In: Buckley-Zistel, Susanne/Kater, Thomas (eds.): Nach Krieg, Gewalt und Repression: Vom schwierigen Umgang mit der Vergangenheit. Baden-Baden: Nomos, 21-37. Carothers, Thomas (2002): The End of the Transition Paradigm. In: Journal of Democracy, 13 (1), 5-21. Díaz Gómez, Catalina (2010): Elementos para un programa administrativo de reparaciones colectivas en Colombia. In: Díaz Gómez, Catalina (ed.): Tareas Pendientes: Propuestas para la formulación de políticas públicas de reparación en Colombia. Bogotá: ICTJ, 269-317.  Stefan Khittel, Jan Pospisil Fletcher, Laurel E./Weinstein, Harvey M./Rowen, James (2009): Context, Timing and the Dynamics of Transitional Justice: A Historical Perspective. In: Human Rights Quarterly 31 (1), 163-220. Kayser-Whande, Undine/Schell-Faucon, Stephanie (2008): Transitional Justice and Civilian Conflict Transformation: Current Research, Future Questions. CCS Working Papers No. 10. Marburg: CCS. Kritz, Neil J. (ed., 1995): Transitional Justice: How Emerging Democracies Reckon with Former Regimes. Vol. I. Washington, DC: USIP. Leebaw, Bronwyn Anne (2008): The Irreconcilable Goals of Transitional Justice. In: Human Rights Quarterly 30 (1), 95-118. Mac Ginty, Roger (2008): Indigenous Peace-Making Versus the Liberal Peace. In: Cooperation and Conflict 43 (2), 139-163. Meister, Robert (2002): Human Rights and the Politics of Victimhood. In: Ethics and International Affairs 16, 91-108. Mendeloff, David (2004): Truth-Seeking, Truth-Telling, and Postconflict Peace- building: Curb the Enthusiasm? In: International Studies Review 6 (3), 355-380. Mosquera Mosquera, Sergio (1997): Afrocitareños esclaizadores y esclavizados. typo- script. Mosquera Rosero-Labbé, Claudia (2007): Reparaciones para negros, afrocolombi- anos y raizales como rescatados de la Trata Negrera Transatlántica y desterrados de la guerra en Colombia. In: Mosquera Rosero-Labbé, Claudia/Barcelos, Luis Claudio (eds.): Afro-reparaciones: Memorias de la Esclavitud y Justicia Repara- tiva para negros, afrocolombianos y raizales. Bogotá: CES, 213-276. Robinson, William I. (1996): Promoting Polyarchy. Globalization, US Intervention, and Hegemony. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Sandole, Dennis J.D./Byrne, Sean/Sandole-Staroste, Ingrid/Senehi, Jessica (eds., 2009): Handbook of Conflict Analysis and Resolution. London/New York: Routledge. Simpson, Grame (2008): One Among Many: The ICC as a Tool of Justice During Transition. In: Waddell, Nicholas/Clark, Phil (eds.): Courting Conflict? Justice, Peace and the ICC in Africa. London: Royal African Society, 73-80. Stotzky, Irwin P. (ed., 1993): Transition to Democracy in Latin America: The Role of the Judiciary. Boulder: Westview Press. Teitel, Ruti G. (2002): Humanity’s Law: Rule of Law for the New Global Politics. In: Cornell International Law Journal 35 (2), 355-387. Webel, Charles/Galtung, Johan (eds., 2007): Handbook of Peace and Conflict Studies. London/New York: Routledge. work_766fm2tvz5ed3ot224qvessv3i ---- УДК: 347.513 М. В. ЖУШМАН, канд. юрид. наук, Національний університет «Юридична академія України імені Ярослава Мудрого», м. Харків ПРИНЦИПИ ЦИВІЛЬНОГО СУДОЧИНСТВА ТА ПРАВОСУДДЯ Проаналізовано основні принципи цивільного процесуального права (судочинства та правосуддя), їх вплив та значення у здійсненні правосуддя та судочинства. Ключові слова: Цивільний процесуальний кодекс, Господарський кодекс, Конституційний Суд, Цивільний кодекс, Кодекс цивільного судочинства, Суд Європейського Союзу, Європейський Союз. На сучасному етапі розвитку суспільства постала необхідність перегляду та вдосконалення значної кількості існуючих уявлень про правові та наукові категорії. Це тим більш актуально, що розбудова в Україні демократичної, соціальної та правової держави потребує проведення конструктивного аналізу досягнень і прорахунків загальнотеоретичної юридичної науки та її подальшого розвитку на зовсім іншій, більш досконалій методологічній основі. Зрозуміло, що діяльність науковців-правників з удосконалення юридичної науки та запровадження досягнень у цій сфері повинна починатись з аналізу основоположних джерел, керівних ідей усього права, тобто з принципів права України взагалі й окремих його галузей зокрема. З цього загального правила не є винятком і цивільне процесуальне право. Принципи цивільного процесуального права формуються, що цілком зрозуміло, не ізольовано, а під впливом загальних принципів усієї правової системи держави. Проблема принципів цивільного процесуального права й досі носить суперечливий характер. Дискусія навколо даної основоположної правової категорії триває вже декілька десятиліть. Ці та інші проблеми й обумовили тематику статті. Ураховуючи актуальність проблеми, не є дивним, що питання принципів цивільного процесуального права і на сьогодні викликає незмінний інтерес вчених-практиків, які займались чи займаються їх дослідженням. Значний 2 внесок у дослідження принципів права, в тому числі й цивільного процесуального, зробили українські вчені України С. С. Алексєєв, В. С. Андрушко, В. Ф. Воронов, О. Ф. Гранін, В. М. Горшеньов, А. С. Довгерт, Н. Б. Зейдер, І. М. Ільїнська, В. В. Комаров, А. М. Колодій, Т. М. Нешатаєва, П. М. Рабінович, М. Й. Штефан, Н. О. Чечина, а також російські науковці В. Б. Авер’янов, С. Н. Абрамова, Г. Є. Абова, В. С. Букіна, О. В. Гетманцев, М. В. Гурвіч, В. О. Котюк, К. С. Юдельсон та ін. Усі вони досліджували такі важливі питання, як сутність та поняття принципів права, виявлення їх змісту, співвідношення з іншими правовими категоріями, їх класифікація та інші проблеми, що однак не завершилося формуванням однозначних концептуальних поглядів на це правове явище. Тому виникає нагальна потреба у розробці нових концептуальних підходів до таких важливих питань, як основні ознаки, поняття і зокрема принципи цивільного процесуального права судочинства і правосуддя, їх класифікації та формування системи. Автор ставить за мету розглянути підходи та найважливіші точки зору вчених щодо принципів судочинства та правосуддя, цивільного процесуального права, їх класифікації та системи в загальній системі права України, а також на основі їх узагальнення та аналізу викласти власне бачення даної проблеми, співвідношення принципів судочинства та правосуддя. Незважаючи на пильну увагу з боку вчених до таких категорій, як принципи права (принципи міжнародного права, окремих галузей права, в тому числі й цивільного процесуального), в науці існують різні їх трактування. Наприклад, в енциклопедичних виданнях термін «принцип» (латин. – principium) визначається як «те, що лежить в основі певної теорії, вчення, науки, світогляду тощо» [3, с. 452]. Принципи права визначаються як основні, загальні (керівні) ідеї, положення, що є основою права, визначають сутність, зміст, призначення і спрямованість правового регулювання суспільних відносин. Правові принципи є тією основою, що характеризує процес зародження, формування, 3 функціонування та розвитку (вдосконалення) права та є вагомими положеннями, на які право повинно спиратись в усіх його проявах (правотворче, правозастосовне, правоохоронне) [9, с. 252]. У міжнародному праві проблема принципів права і кожної його галузі, в тому числі й цивільної процесуальної, обумовлюється тим, що принципи відбивають основу, її суть, характер і риси. У міжнародному праві загальновизнаною є дія принципу верховенства права, який закраплений у низці міжнародних нормативно-правових актів як загального (Загальна декларація прав людини), так і регіонального рівнів (Статут Ради Європи, європейська Конвенція про захист прав людини, Африканська хартія прав людини та народів). Відповідно до ст. 8 Конституції в Україні також закріплений, визнається і діє принцип верховенства права. Основний Закон України має найвищу юридичну силу. Закони та інші нормативно-правові акти приймаються на основі Конституції України й повинні відповідати їй [8, с. 135]. Норми Конституції України є нормами прямої дії. Звернення до суду для захисту конституційних прав і свобод людини і громадянина безпосередньо на підставі Конституції України гарантується. Стаття 55 Конституції України регламентує, що права і свободи людини і громадянина захищаються судом. Здійснення правосуддя виключно судами є одним із основоположних принципів цивільного судочинства. Принципи є найбільш узагальненою категорією права України й окремих його галузей нарівні з такими, як предмет і метод, правовідносини тощо. Тому інтенсивні дослідження принципів права, в тому числі й цивільного процесуального знаходяться в центрі уваги вчених. Дослідження цієї проблеми ускладнюється і тим, що в процесуальній літературі та судовій практиці питання про поняття і зміст принципів вирішується по-різному. Одні автори під принципами права розуміють загальні керівні положення, на думку інших принципи цивільного процесуального права – керівні основи цивільного процесу [14, с. 30]. 4 Так, С. С. Алексєєв під принципами права має на увазі виражені в праві вихідні нормативно-правової засади, що характеризують його зміст, основи, закріплені в ньому основи суспільного життя [1, с. 98, 99]. О. С. Комаров розглядає принципи права як основні ідеї, організаційні характерні ознаки правотворчості [6, с. 237]. Г. А. Свердлик під правовими принципами розуміє керівні положення, його основні засади, які відбивають об’єктивні закономірності, тенденції та потреби суспільства, що обумовлюють сутність усієї системи, галузі чи інституту права і мають в силу їх правового закріплення загальнообов’язкове значення [11, с. 17]. Аналогічної думки дотримується і Є. А. Суханов [13, с. 24]. Правові принципи, зазначає В. М. Семенов, це такі його якісні особливості, що складають ідейно-політичні основи, виражають його класову спрямованість, конкретний соціальний тип, специфічні властивості права. Саме за принципами право однієї суспільно-економічної формації відрізняється від права іншої формації [12, с. 30]. Значний внесок у дослідження даної проблеми зробила й українська юридична наука. На думку О. А. Пушкіна, принципи права – основоположні ідеї (основи, положення), у відповідності з якими здійснюється регулювання суспільних відносин [11, с. 10]. У спеціальній монографічній праці «Принципи права України» А. М. Колодій робить висновок, що «…принципи права – це такі відправні ідеї існування права, які виражають найважливіші закономірності і підвалини даного типу держави і права, є однопорядковими із сутністю права і становлять його головні риси, відзначаються універсальністю, вищою імперативністю і загальною значимістю, відповідають об’єктивній необхідності побудови і зміцнення певного суспільного ладу» [4, с. 98-99]. В юридичній літературі висловлено й інші точки зору на визначення принципів права. Проте, незважаючи на існування великої кількості різноманітних, інколи навіть протилежних поглядів щодо сутності, поняття системи, структури класифікації характеристики принципів права, більшість правників дотримуються позиції, що принципи права – це керівні положення права, його основні засади, основоположні ідеї, які виражають об’єктивні закономірності, 5 тенденції та потреби суспільства, що визначають сутність всієї системи, галузі чи інституту права, які мають в силу їх правового закріплення загальнообов’язкове значення. На нашу думку, найбільш повне й аргументоване визначення поняття принципів цивільного процесуального права наведено в підручнику «Курс цивільного процесуального права» за редакцією професора В. В. Комарова [8]. Принципи цивільного процесуального права, вказується в ньому, – це виражені в нормах цивільного процесуального права незаперечні за своєю природою вимоги до суду та учасників цивільного процесу, які конкретизують його зміст та визначають порядок здійснення правосуддя в цивільних справах. Свою конкретизацію і спеціалізацію загально-правові принципи знаходять у галузях права, кожна з яких залежно від свого предмета й метода характеризується власним набором принципів юридичного опосередкування даної сфери суспільних відносин. Система права України за внутрішньої єдності водночас залежно від предмета та методу, які, безсумнівно, вносять специфіку і до системи принципів, надаючи їм галузеву спрямованість і окрасу, поділяється на галузі. Слід погодитись з В. М. Семеновим, який зазначає, що галузеві принципи конкретизують відносно галузі права загально-правові принципи [12, с. 5–7]. При цьому необхідно враховувати, що особливістю принципів права є те, що вони не розрізненні, а перебувають у чіткій системі та субординації, відбивають не тільки властивості правової системи в цілому, а й визначають, з урахуванням предмета та методу певної галузі, місце кожного з принципів у житті суспільства. Особливо це виявляється в принципах судочинства та правосуддя. Загально-правові принципи та принципи міжнародного права, що мають загальний характер, більш конкретно втілюються в принципах кожної галузі (див. [9]). Основні принципи права отримують також специфічну модифікацію у галузях права і сферах правоутворення, правореалізації та правоохорони. Отже, враховуючи характер принципів за їх сферою впливу на певну групу (групи) суспільних відносин, вони поділяються на загально-правові, 6 оскільки поширюються на право взагалі та галузеві відносини, врегульовані правом певної його галузі, наприклад, цивільного процесу. Подібної точки зору дотримується також О. В. Шутенко та ін. [17; 12, с. 22; 13, с. 9]. На думку С. С. Алексєєва, принципи галузі права (галузеві) слід розмежовувати й залежно від певних її інститутів, на які вони впливають, галузеві принципи можна поділяти і на принципи правових інститутів [1]. Проте В. А. Кройтор дотримується протилежної думки, згідно з якою група принципів окремих правових інститутів або стадій процесу існувати не може, оскільки порушується єдність системи принципів цивільного процесуального права [7, с. 18]. У свою чергу В. А. Андрушко зазначає: «Принципи цивільного процесуального права поширюють свою дію на всю галузь права, складовими якої саме і є процесуальні інститути та норми» [2, с. 25]. Російський процесуаліст Н. О. Чечина стверджує: «…єдина система принципів процесуального права в цілому виключає можливість існування відокремлених принципів для окремих стадій процесуальної діяльності або окремо взятого інституту. Той чи інший принцип повинен мати визначальне значення і знаходити найбільший прояв в одній із стадій діяльності або в окремих інститутах, але загальне його значення визначається взаємодією з іншими принципами, впливом їх на діяльність суду в цілому» [15, с. 80]. Важливо підкреслити, що до загальноправових принципів права слід віднести, в першу чергу, ті положення-принципи, які прямо сформульовані у вказаних раніше європейських Декларації, Конвенції, Статуті та Конституції України. Застосування цивільного процесуального законодавства має здійснюватися у межах Конституції як фундаментального нормативного акта в правовій системі, а теоретичні моделі та наукові концепції, які виконують інтерпретаційну функцію, повинні мати конституційне обґрунтування. При цьому принципове значення має науковий аналіз конституційних підстав правосуддя і судочинства. Як справедливо вказує В. В. Комаров, конституційні принципи цивільного правосуддя і судочинства – це певні доктринальні положення, які 7 мають інтерпретаційне значення наукових парадигм, і які визначають, з одного боку, сферу конституційно-правового регулювання судової влади і правосуддя, а з іншого є передумовами, конституційними складовими режиму цивільного судочинства [6, с. 193]. У законодавстві та юридичній літературі правосуддя і судочинство нерідко ототожнюються, досить часто вживаються як синоніми, проте це не можна визнати обґрунтованим. Вірно, на нашу думку, на помилковість такого твердження вказує В. В. Комаров: «Судова юрисдикція, особливе повноваження органів судової влади, тому в цивільному судочинстві не всі і не всякі процесуальні дії судді (суду) є діями по здійсненню правосуддя» [5, с. 193]. Наприклад, навряд чи можна віднести до правосуддя дії судді, який запропонував позивачу виправити помилку, допущену ним при сплаті судового збору чи усунути помилки в позовній заяві, які не впливають на вирішення справи по суті, фіксування судового процесу тощо – це, безумовно, відноситься до судочинства. Правосуддя повинно розглядатися як здійснення права і свобод суб’єктів права через низку судових процедур, які притаманні саме судочинству. Функцію здійснення правосуддя держава покладає виключно на суди. Вони є органами судової влади, яка, згідно зі ст. 6 Конституції України, діє незалежно від законодавчої і виконавчої влади. Інші органи держаної влади та посадові особи, не дивлячись на те, що мають право впливу на суб’єктивні права та обов’язки суб’єктів відносин, позбавлені права перебирати на себе функцію і повноваження, які є компетенцією органів правосуддя. Виключно суди виконують примусові повноваження державної влади, які знайшли закріплення в Конституції, ЦПК та в іншому цивільному процесуальному законодавстві. Призначенням судів є також здійснення захисту гарантованих Конституцією кожному прав і свобод (ст. 55). Роль суду в цьому значно підвищено новим положенням про те, що компетенцію суду поширено на всі правовідносини, що виникають у державі. Відповідно до цього основний 8 загальноправовий принцип знайшов своє закріплення в ст. 124 Конституції, яка регламентує: «Правосуддя в Україні здійснюється виключно судами». Водночас зазначається, що «судочинство здійснюється Конституційним судом України та судами загальної юрисдикції». Отже, застосування термінів «правосуддя» і «судочинство» в різному їх значенні в одній і тій же статті дає підстави для висновку, що правосуддя і судочинство є відмінними як щодо термінології їх вживання, так і за своїм змістом та значенням. Діяльність зі здійснення судочинства, окрім судді, виконують й інші працівники суду та учасники цивільного процесу, зокрема секретар судового засідання, судовий розпорядник та ін., наприклад, підготовка судових викликів і повідомлень, перевірка наявності та з’ясування причин відсутності осіб, яких було викликано до суду, забезпечення фіксування судового засідання технічними засобами, оформлення матеріалів та іншої судової документації (статті 48, 49 ЦПК України). Не викликає сумніву, що від якості та своєчасності дій секретаря, розпорядника, експерта та інших учасників судового процесу залежить належне здійснення судового процесу і, врешті-решт, здійснення суддею правосуддя, прийняття ним обґрунтованого і законного рішення. Принципи (основні засади) судочинства викладено в ст. 129 Конституції України, ЦПК, КАСУ та Законі України «Про судоустрій і статус суддів». Сформульована в ч. 1 ст. 129 конституційна норма про те, що судді при здійсненні правосуддя незалежні й підкоряються лише закону, має важливе значення як загальний принцип судочинства і правосуддя. Зміст вказаної норми свідчить про те, що і принципи судочинства, і принципи правосуддя спрямовані на досягнення єдиної цілі і мети – захист прав і свобод людини і громадянина. Виражені в них вимоги до суду та учасників цивільного процесу, концептуалізують їх зміст і основну спрямованість та визначальний порядок здійснення правосуддя в цивільних справах. Принципи судочинства і правосуддя є взаємообумовленими, взаємопов’язаними й характеризуються відсутністю в них протистояння. Наприклад, як для судочинства, так і для здійснення правосуддя 9 необхідне дотримання принципу законності. Без забезпечення рівності всіх учасників судового процесу перед законом і судом, змагальності сторін щодо свободи в наданні ними суду своїх доказів і в доведенні перед судом їх переконливості, рішення чи постанова суду як акт правосуддя не можуть бути законними й обґрунтованими. Це дає підстави дійти висновку, що принципи судочинства та правосуддя є комплексними, взаємообумовлюючими та взаємозалежними. Це такі основоположні ідеї, доктринальні положення, наукові парадигми, які є віссю діяльності суду щодо здійснення судочинства і правосуддя. З цього приводу В. В. Комаров цілком слушно зауважує, що судова юрисдикція – це особливе повноваження органів судової влади, тому в цивільному судочинстві не всі і не всякі процесуальні дії судді (суду) є діями по здійсненню правосуддя. Правосуддя в цивільних справах стосовно цивільного процесу має субстанціальний характер, і в категоріальному аспекті вони співвідносяться як сутність і явище. Отже, судочинство (цивільний процес) є забезпечувальним відносно правосуддя. Без судочинства здійснення правосуддя неможливе. З урахуванням вище сказаного, судочинство – це правовий цивільно-процесуальний механізм правосуддя. Усе це дозволяє дійти висновку, що дослідження принципів цивільного процесуального права є необхідним процесом і потребує постійної уваги. Водночас дана діяльність має бути концептуально, змістовно та термінологічно узгоджена із загальними правовими ідеями, висновками та правовими прогнозами, а також мораллю. Список літератури: 1. Алексеев С. С. Общая теория права / С. С. Алексеев. – М. : Юрид. лит., 1981. – Т. І. – 510 с. 2. Андрушко А. В. Принцип диспозитивності цивільного процесуального права в Україні : монографія / А. В. Андрушко. – Х., 2006. – 180 с. 3. Енциклопедичний словник / за заг ред. д-ра філол. наук, проф. В. В. Дубінського. – Х. : Клуб сімейного дозвілля, 2010. – 606 с. 4. Колодій А. М. Принципи права України : монографія / А. М. Колодій. – К. : Юрінком Інтер, 1998. – 208 с. 5. Комаров В. В. Теоретичні та практичні проблеми реалізації Конституції України / 10 В. В. Комаров // Зб. тез доп. та наук. повід. учасн. Всеукр. наук.-практ. конф. (29-30 червня 2006 р.). – Х., 2006. – С. 191–196. 6. Комаров С. А. Общая теория права / С. А. Комаров. – М. : Юрид. лит., 1999. – 535 с. 7. Кройтор В. А. Система принципів цивільного процесуального права / В. А. Кройтор // Вісник ХНУВС. – Х., 2008. – С. 15–22. 8. Курс цивільного процесу : підручник / за ред. В. В. Комарова. – Х. : Право, 2011. – 1351 с. 9. Мала енциклопедія теорії держави і права / за заг. ред. Ю. Л. Бошицького. – К. : Вид-во Європейського ун-ту, 2010. – 366 с. 10. Пушкін А. А. Гражданское право : ученик / А. А. Пушкін. – К. : Вища шк., 1977. – Т. І. – 456 с. 11. Свердлык Г. А. Принципы советского гражданского права / Г. А. Свердлык. – Красноярск, 1985. – 480 с. 12. Семенов В. М. Понятие и система принципов советского гражданского процессуального права / В. М. Семенов // Сб. учен. тр. – Свердловск, 1964. – Вып. 2. – С. 179–239. 13. Суханов Е. А. Гражданское право / Е. А. Суханов. – М. : БЕК, 1994. – Т. І. – 376 с. 14. Цивільне процесуальне право України : підручник / за ред. В. В. Комарова – Х. : Право, 1999. – 590 с. 15. Чечина Н. А. Принципы советского гражданского процессуального права / Н. А. Чечина // Правоведение. – 1960. – № 3. – С. 78–83. 16. Шутенко О. В. Проблеми диспозитивності в цивільному судочинстві : автореф. дис. … канд. юрид. наук / О. В. Шутенко. – Х., 2003. – 19 с. Жушман М. В. Принципы гражданского судопроизводства и правосудия. Рассмотрены и исследованы основные принципы гражданского процессуального права (судопроизводства и правосудия), их влияние и значение в осуществлении правосудия и судопроизводства. Ключевые слова: ГПК – Гражданско-процессуальный кодекс, ХК – Хозяйственный кодекс, ГК – Гражданский кодекс, КС – Конституционный Суд, КАСУ – Кодекс административного судопроизводства Украины, Суд ЕС – Суд Европейского Союза, ЕС – Европейский Союз. Zhushman M. V. Principles of civil procedure and justice. The basic principles of civil procedural law (proceedings in civil causes and justice), their influence and importance in the administration of justice and judicial proceedings were examined and studied Key words: CCP – Code of Civil Procedure, EC – The Economic Code, CC – the Civil Code, The CC – The Constitutional Court, CALP – he Code of Administrative Legal Procedure of Ukraine, The ECJ – Court of the European Union, the EU – the European Union. work_77d7oz7b25cbjalenh4jgitovi ---- Bharati Law Review, Oct. – Dec., 2014 88     RESTORATIVE JUSTICE: THE NEW PARADIGM IN THE PROVINCE OF JUSTICE IN INDIA? Dr. Puranjoy Ghosh∗ The ‘thoughts’ about justice are so divergent and equivocal that any attempt to design the panacea within the rubric of justice would be a perfect disharmony. The scholastic experiments so far being continued to achieve the utilitarianism in the province of justice are being concluded to the adage, ‘every justice brings an injustice’. Hence, the intellectual bickering on diverse perspectives with the changing needs of the society make the evolutionary process to achieve justice dynamic. The present paper delves into the provinces or doctrines or ideas or concepts of ‘restorative justice’ not to figure out the flaws in the same rather to make a journey over the assumptions of restorative justice in criminal justice administration, particularly in India. The attempt of restorative justice, precisely, apart from the perpetrators and victims, is to accommodate within the fold of the legal frameworks to redress the harm or injury caused to the communities and with the view of reforming and reintegrating contributory role from the ends of communities in upholding social justice as well. Telling incidents about restorative justice inspires more liberalization of civil liberties in the framework of administration of justice while variegated growing concern about public-order and safety irritates the comparison for effective administration between such liberalized approach and pragmatic approach. Again, the attempt to establish peaceful relations among the members of the communities, social control, to ensure equality and cultural expectations or even to reduce recidivism have been mobilizing the disproportionate socio- economic or socio-cultural or even socio-political factors, like communal politics, casteism, etc., and perpetuate conflicts among different communities in any multicultural country like India. Part – I Introduction In the long history of the study of administration of criminal justice the question of attainability has typically been a central part of the inquiry. Indeed, the question of whether particular goals are achievable by specified means or by any means is an elementary and                                                              ∗ Assistant Professor, School of Law, KIIT University, Bhubaneswar, Odisha, India. Bharati Law Review, Oct. – Dec., 2014 89     unavoidable question about any concept or idea or theory of justice. Human being, a composite of impulsion and reason reflects upon his conduct and observe disharmonies, correlates means and ends. Acceptance or adaptation of a particular principle of conduct in directing one’s activities may be called as following of ‘norm’: an abstract pattern to set limits for behaviour in the society. The operative norm is one that is not merely entertained in the mind but is considered worthy of following in actual behaviour, thus, one feels that one ought to conform to it. Hence, every society within the fold of its system permits its members some freedom to pursue self- interested goals within the permissible limits. Many transactions, while quite legitimate, involve more or less latent conflicts of interests, and there must be mechanisms for counteracting such elements of conflict with some emphasis on solidarity or on interests that transcend the conflict. Society is an aggregation of individual selves and basic social commitments of the members are to stay away of others’ way. Any members being a free-willing agent of one’s self while engages oneself to trespass on the preserves of other(s) the question of ‘justice’ comes to the fore. And again, cry for ‘justice’ does not arise until the collective expectations of ‘demand-supply’ is severely imbalanced. Inherently some members of the human society are not inclined towards the maintenance of social norms or orders and coercive force of punishment to maintain social norms and institutionalized order is but the effective alternative. The formulation of the doctrine of ‘justice’ and subsuming the total philosophy of life and ideals of socio-political or socio-economic existence under ‘justice’ is a peculiar characteristic and aspect of the purpose of law. The debate about ‘what is justice’ started in Greek thought, is still burning issue without any precise definition. Thought about ‘justice’ invokes diverse elements, like, social, political, economic, logical, psychological, and consequently any method or ideas or concepts emphasize one or some of them by ignoring other or others accomplished with the honest mischief of being insufficient or incomplete in its approach. The composite appearance of ‘justice’ has made it to be beyond any prefix. More than that it may be one’s own ideological construction, or intellectual preference or critical reflection or emotional reaction but its appeal to human beings is so great that no legal theory can ignore it without the risk of being incomplete and inadequate. Though ‘justice’ is not amenable to logical and scientific approach as there is no unanimity about its settled content and meaning, yet it is a sort of ‘demand notice’ which the members of civil society direct against the established legal frameworks, social orders and political institutions and agencies. And again, the homogeneity Bharati Law Review, Oct. – Dec., 2014 90     as well as heterogeneity of the bundle of demands of the members of the society necessitates streamlining of most predominant and efficacious legal framework. In brief, it is theory of expectation, the net result of human desires and demands–the ends or values of law which are assessed by objective determination in the light of the practical working of law. By ‘restorative justice’ meant one comprehensive mechanism within the fold of regular legal framework to accelerate the speedy disposal of the legal issues aiming at to achieve social peace and order as well as least grievances in processual justice. Hence, it is one ancillary mechanism to dispel the social belief of ‘injustice’ to the victim, offender as well as the community. The provinces enfolded within the processes of restorative justice are: i. the ‘want’ of the survivors/victims from the existing system of justice; ii. responsiveness of the prevalent system of justice to the identified needs; iii. possibility of removal of the aberrations caused in the interpersonal relationship between the survivor/victim and offender through such restorative process; iv. experience perceived by the community at large in such reparation process; and v. impact on reformative process of justice as well. In short, providing the scope of restorative justice means introduction another subsidiary procedural mechanism in the legal framework of the country for, in order to make the restorative process of justice functional besides the fold of existing legal framework in India would require a different set of operating agents who are to play dual role like, to act as community service and social counseling also as being the members of ‘reparation body’ of the society to provide ‘justice’. The chief purpose of restorative justice is to restore peace and harmonious co-existence of conflicting interests in the society. In addition to it, it also promotes the concerned community to take effective observatory role in rehabilitation of the offender to the mainstream of the society. In such process what is deemed to have been changing is the pro-functional importance of the community/communities and to an extent the majority and minority role of the divided groups within the fold of that local community or between different communities. Any society is composed of heterogeneous communities and in any community various categories of members like adult-children, men-women, literate-illiterate, rich- poor, powerful-improvised, etc., and again cultural diversity in India also makes the differences in the choices, habits, values, social Bharati Law Review, Oct. – Dec., 2014 91     stigma, cultures, etc, from one local community to other. Hence, to characterize a uniform social design applicable uniformly irrespective of cultural diversity would accentuate the intricacies in devising such reparation process. The efficiency and effectiveness of the traditional and customary systems of administration of justice was based on the cultures, religion, practices, consensus, aspirations, of the diverse communities of the society. In a dispute situation, familiarity with other members of one’s society helps to smoothen the edges for more cooperative and acceptable resolution of the dispute.1 Ultimately close kinship, friendly, good neighbourly relationships would enable to promote peace, unity, harmony and progress of the society and by restorative process these social control techniques are tend to achieve with systemic perfection. Intrusion of difference of opinions would evolve in that, that whatever rules and standard-norms are being set by the state in choosing the operative agents for constituting the local community group to ensure restorative process, an in-depth analysis in a case where victim-offender both lead hand-to-mouth standard of living or whatsoever social parameters as stated above would hardly involve any safe resolution of the social relationships in such reintegration conference of the harms so caused due to one or more of such factors. Again, some other significant aspects, to be taken into account while devising such restorative process are: the presence of the key participants in such negotiation process to restore–because regard to be had about the privacies of the parties to such restorative process leading to determine about the presence of member(s) of the concerned localities or presence of the social activists or say from the ends of the state administration police or judges etc., are also significant. Part – II Indigenous and Pre-British Legal System in India “In a world of responsive law, ……… law’s power does not stem from tradition or its formal pedigree alone, but also from its persuasiveness as good public policy. In a world of responsive law, legal institutions–courts, regulatory agencies, alternative dispute resolution bodies, police departments–are periodically studied and redesigned to improve their ability to fulfill public expectations.”2                                                              1 NANSO OKAFO, INTERDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH SERIES IN ETHNIC, GENDER AND CLASS RELATIONS: RECONSTRUCTING JUSTICE IN A POST COLONY 9-10 (Ashgate Publishing Ltd. 2009). 2 Robert A. Kagan, Introduction to PHILIPPE NONET’S & PHILIP SELZNICK, TOWARD RESPONSIVE LAW: LAW AND SOCIETY IN TRANSITION xxiv–xxv (Transaction Publishers 2001). Bharati Law Review, Oct. – Dec., 2014 92     By restorative justice what is being promoted is the responsive law. Traditions, customs, indigenous principles of laws are sensibly and unpretentiously inculcate the indigenous essence of law and legal system and if any legal framework is made on such responses would undeniably accentuate the laws more efficacious and effective due to its inherent acquired aspirations in the process of law. In any country the utility and relevancy of law is tested and perceived through social internalization and cultural evolution of the populace in the societies. The choices of the communities to follow or continue to follow some habits would interpret the values in such practices of such communities and such components of social lives would form the compatibility and tradition in setting social norms, and adherence to such practices would set the legal tradition of the society to regulate the individual relations within on different facets of livelihood of members of these communities as well. The chequered history of evolution of the present legal system in India would clearly purport that the except in few areas of family laws the traditional components and system of dispute resolution has almost been amputated rather gradually customized with the rules of common law principles by precedents and analogy. Thus in a country of multicultural complex societies like ours the living sources of governing rules of human relationships in the communities, the traditional consensual conciliatory character of dispute resolution have been swept from today’s adversarial character of official rules. The disintegrated political approaches of the rulers, however, encouraged several invaders to invade this country and to introduce their preferred dispute resolution systems for better administration and governance of the relations of their subjects resulting in loss of authoritative uniform social norms to evolve. The colonial economy tempted the colonial administrators to articulate and regulate the characters and practices of indigenous dispute resolution process by passing regulations to that effect.3 Extension of judicial control in the better governance the colonial administration thus, limited legal administration and concept of limited jurisdiction and with the passage of time the traditional legal practices and sources of law became the flexible legal process.4 Mostly the political features of a country influences in shaping the socio-economic, cultural and legal dimensions and developments of the country.5 Thus, local practices in different local communities those having stronghold on its members and desired effect in governing the                                                              3 LAUREN A. BENTON, LAW AND COLONIAL CULTURES (Cambridge University Press 2001). 4 Id. 5 MC LEOD, JOHN, HISTORY OF INDIA (Greenwood Press, Westport, CT, USA 2002). Bharati Law Review, Oct. – Dec., 2014 93     individual relationship within those communities in the country at times boil down the established legal-norms and systems, e.g., different traditional tribunals, say, kangaroo courts or say Khap Panchayats and inspires the debate of popular legality of official rules. For instance, the incident of January 20146 in West Bengal about the decision of rape in Salishi Sabha [say Kangaroo Court] where participation in community framework was self-styled for restorative process but the decision has undermined the public confidence in such restorative process of justice. Again, the incident of April 3, 20147 the decision of such community led victim housewife to commit suicide setting herself ablaze as the victim was prevented from a filing a police complaint about the rape wherein the reason substantiated by such sabha was that the rapist has apologized to victim. Fact that, the survivor’s family has been enjoying sufferance of deep psychological pressures of being ostracized as the decision of such Salishi Sabha has been defied by complaining to the police. On both counts the incidents are of tribal communities to who the kangaroo court is supreme. The points may be argued that they are not educated and don’t understand the normal system of law but the reflection of influential members of such community bodies in deliberative democracy and people’s choice on justice makes the difference about values of justice.                                                              6 A tribal woman, aged around 20 years, was allegedly gang-raped at Subalpur village under Labhpur police station area on January 21 by the accused as punishment for having an affair with a man from another community [commonly known as Labhpur incident]. 7 TIMES OF INDIA, Apr. 3, 2014 (Malda): A mother of three committed suicide on Wednesday after a kangaroo court questioned her character and let off the rapist lightly. The woman could not accept the humiliation. “She did not sleep all night and set herself on fire at dawn,” said her husband. She died in hospital late on Wednesday. Her children were at home on Monday when neighbour, Nabin Mandal, 21, allegedly barged in and raped her. The woman's husband was incensed and attacked Nabin but was held back by villagers who suggested they convene a village court to ‘settle the issue’. A kangaroo court was held that evening. The woman and her tormenter were brought face to face, intensifying her trauma. The sabha ‘decided’ that Nabin would apologize to her by touching her feet and that in ‘future such cases’ the rapist would have to pay Rs 25,000 to the survivor. The woman and her husband were shocked. They refused to accept the verdict. “How can a rapist be absolved of such a crime by touching the victim’s feet? We protested even in the meeting. It has only brought more humiliation to my wife. They used vulgar language and questioned my wife’s character,” said the husband. Social Welfare Minister Sabitri Mitra, who is also the local MLA, was quick to blame the Opposition. “We got to know that CPM and Congress men were present in the kangaroo court and connived to deny justice to the victim,” she said. District CPM Secretary Ambar Mitra rubbished the allegation and said: “When will the government learn not to see political colour and ensure justice for rape victims?” Malda SP said they hope to arrest the main accused soon. Bharati Law Review, Oct. – Dec., 2014 94     The pro-functional approach of these local communities for settling disputes outside the existing legal systems highly influence the members of those communities and fewer cases are brought forth in official justice rendering system. In numerous cases, for example, where fatwas are issued by different boards established under the tutelage of All India Muslim Personal Law Board or similar agencies in different localities of Union of India for the purpose of resolving the disputes alternatively, within the members of the communities in conformity with the religious mandates issues have been raised in a recent Public Interest Litigation (PIL) like, issuing of such fatwas are illegal, illegitimate and unconstitutional; resolving of the disputes in such alternative fashion strives to establish a parallel judicial system etc. Union of India has pleaded on it appearance to such PIL that these kind of boards act like arbitrator, mediator, negotiator, or conciliator in the matter of family disputes or civil disputes and not in criminal matters and categorized these as alternative dispute resolution mechanism for expeditious, amicable and inexpensive settlement of disputes outside the court. Meanwhile All India Muslim Personal Law Board has stated it to be an informal justice delivery system. The Supreme Court of India8 viewed the status of fatwas from the perspective of objective requirements of a valid law and efficacy thereof and declared those fatwas as not legally binding as they are not made by competent authority like legislature. The court further observed that: “They are not part of the corpus juris of the state” but “an opinion, only an expert is expected to give.”9 The oddity in the observation is that the court has opined again that: “However, as the fatwa gets strength from the religion; it causes serious psychological impact on the person intending not to abide by that.”10 Thus, the Supreme Court has felt the pulse of the psychological impact and the ordeal thereof likely to be enjoyed by the parties to such disputes in the event of such fatwas by such types of local boards or agencies in the respective local communities but the Supreme Court has not taken venture to recommend some mandatory guidelines which are to be complied with by such responsible local bodies or agencies for advancing the restorative justice in such alternative dispute resolution mechanism. Predominantly, these types of fatwas are closely linked to the traditional practices evolved in due course of                                                              8 Decision in Writ Petition (Civil) No. 386 of 2005; Vishwa Lochan Madan v. Union of India & Ors., passed on July 7, 2014 in the Bench of Hon’ble Justice Mr. Chandramauli Kr. Prasad and Hon’ble Justice Pinaki Chandra Ghose, available at judis.nic.in/supremecourt/imgs1.aspx?filename=41747. 9 Id. at 12. 10 Id. at 13. Bharati Law Review, Oct. – Dec., 2014 95     times are like, non-cooperation and social ostracize from the communities, etc. In a restorative process of justice system such an alternative body or agency is required to be constituted for the reparation process but how far such bodies or agencies would satisfy the perceived goal in effectuating the restorative justice system is subject to repeated inquiries and evaluations as well. The underlying possessive character of such operating agents in capturing such power-steering in the guise of rendering restorative process within such local community would be to take a control on it and again may adversely affect the noble pursuits of justice and harmonious order in such restorative process. Alternative Dispute Resolution (ADR) system for rendering justice in India has been set up on the bedrock of subsidizing the operational extent of prescribed official rules for downsizing the delay in disposal of disputes. For example, for the realization of debts due of the banks the process of negotiation and mediation what are being encouraged in Lok Adalat is to pay the lesser amount and thus the disputes are being disposed of earmarking ‘realised on full satisfaction’, thus creating the loss of social wealth by those who are abusing the process of law of the land. The progressive move towards liberalism of the human civilization expands the ambit of basic needs and thus placing pressure upon the administrative machineries of the State to address varied unlimited demands for allocating the resources in a consistent manner. Increasing population causes increased-demands within the limited pool of resources. Thus, on the one hand the dilution of social wealth and on the other increasing pressure of demands developing the consistent pressure to find out the balancing legal mechanism and legal framework as well to harmonize and facilitate the balance of conflicting interests or say the competing interests in the society. Similar opportunities of concessions are being enlarged in criminal proceedings of the country as well by introducing Plea Bargaining. The existence of Section 320 of the Code of Criminal Procedure, 1973 (Cr.P.C.) has earmarked the petty offences by furnishing a list of those offences what are compoundable and the introduction of Plea Bargaining in 2005 has created another segment by the strength what concession may be pleaded [or bargained?] before the court to absolve the rigour of the penalty. This mutual pre-trial negotiations or say deal between the victim and offenders through their agents [read Advocates] requires judicial endorsement. Restorative process is an additional procedural edition of legal system by enlarging the opportunities to the members of local community members in whose communities such offence/offences have been committed to Bharati Law Review, Oct. – Dec., 2014 96     effectuate such mutual pre-trial deal. Democratization of norms should be the be-all and end-all in the framework of such community participatory model of administration of justice and certainly to achieve the desired objects of speedy disposal of disputes as well as utilitarian approach in the administration of justice. But in reality it works out differently due to imperfect accountability of the cultural dimensions of such members of the localities or communities. By abusing the process of such legal provisions there is the erosion of social faith in adjudication of criminal proceedings. For example, the terrorists’ activities at Mumbai in 9/11, 2008 evaporated the confidence of the foreigners concerning the ‘Public Peace’ and ‘Law and Order’ in India–the primary tasks of the official machinery to maintain and loss of what affected the tourism industry of the country. Therefore, the loss of public confidence in the official rules of a country affects the country in developing the social wealth as well as the values in the official norms. Restoration process could not provide the restorative touch in case of certain offences like, the ordeal passed by a rape victim [children and women both inclusive], the child-labour, terrorism [both waged by militia and state sponsored], political vendetta, scam those erode the public and social wealth substantially etc., rather to follow the compensatory mechanism in affording the remedial appendages. What is well settled is that the relevancy of psychology on making the differences in socio-cultural dimensions of different communities of the societies has been well established in the context of i) their naïve metaphysical systems at a deep level; ii) their tacit epistemologies; and iii) even the nature of their cognitive processes– the ways by which they know the world.11 Alike other attempts for crystallizing a universal psychology12 Restorative process is one of such attempt, directed to promote the social relationship and people’s choices that are in consonance and consistence of the fundamental principles of justice of the country. Problems underlies in the growing understanding of diverse opinions and values in shaping and giving effect to such fundamental principles in a country inhabited by multicultural diverse communities, say for example, the futility in                                                              11 R.E. Nisbett, K. Peng, I. Choi, & A. Noenzayan, Culture and Systems of Thought: Holistic Versus Analytic Cognition, 108 (2) PSYCHOLOGICAL REVIEW 291–310 (2001). 12 INDIGENOUS PSYCHOLOGIES: RESEARCH AND EXPERIENCE IN CULTURAL CONTEXT (U. Kim & J.W. Berry eds., Sage Publication, New Delhi 1993); U. Kim & Y.S. Park, Integrated Analysis of Indigenous Psychologies: Comments and Extensions of Ideas Presented by Shams, Jackson, Hewang & Kashima, ASIAN JOURNAL OF SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGY 8, 75–95 (2005); Psychology in India Revisited–Developments in the Discipline, 3 APPLIED SOCIAL AND ORGANIZATIONAL PSYCHOLOGY (J. Pandey ed., Sage, New Delhi 2004). Bharati Law Review, Oct. – Dec., 2014 97     giving the concrete shape of Uniform Civil Code even after achieving independence after long 66 years. The official rules and norms are not the organic growth of the society, it has not fully evolved out of spontaneous urge of the societies rather emphasis is given to officiate the rules introduced by British and the inhabitants are grown acclimatized with those official norms. Basically, the systemic structural frameworks so far characterized in any community around the globe to develop human-behaviours’ regulatory mechanism have perceived the demands of the members of the community on the grounds of commonalities and greater values. Scrutinizing the values of greater interests through rationalized self- interest of human being in the society the regulatory agencies and its frameworks coordinated the limitations and consequences in case of breach of those. Hedonism in human behavioural patterns in society is no exception but increasing frequency of such behaviours in almost every walk of life stultify the values, both social and moral, and affects the legal system to confine the human behaviours and conducts in more efficient ways. The efficiency of law cannot only be achieved on its mere compliance rather the more it would uphold the values the more it becomes responsive to the society and secures the efficacy in the society. Every member of the society is the stakeholder of the legal system of the society and preservation of such values, be it in law, legal systems or in human behaviours, would enhance the maximum in paying allegiance to such responsive law and legal system of the country. Consultation with local stakeholders to instill confidence in public mindset about the social values of the public services tendered by the Public Bodies United Kingdom has come up with the Public Services (Social Value) Act, 2012. This attempt has enveloped the aspirations of the exponential stakeholders of the society by dint of appreciating people’s perception for efficient performance of the public bodies in the long run in furtherance of administration of justice in democratic state. In our country in the guise of reformation and to curb down the ill-practices several committees like bodies are given a shape to preserve social values of the official rules and norms to make those more responsive to the citizens and ultimately ends in promoting more corruptions and mismanagement of social wealth. The transition shift of justice system, in particular in criminal administration of justice, from pragmatic rigourous legal system, e.g., infliction of injuries to the wrongdoer or to develop the fear-psychosis for achieving deterrence effect to more responsive legal system, i.e., to enquire into the detailed particulars of the social facts and causes, directing or tend to direct the behaviours of the wrongdoers to the pattern of wrongdoing and to comprehend the purpose of ends of law Bharati Law Review, Oct. – Dec., 2014 98     ‘restorative justice’ is one of such dimensions in the chapter of administration of justice. But this is one additional procedural framework introduced and conscious effort of speedy disposal of disputes how far would be successful is significant and important. For example, at one point of time breathable ‘air’ had been considered to be available at a zero price and it was known as to be a free good. With the advancement of civilization good, quality, breathable air is not free and recent trends of the judiciary from ‘Polluters Pay’ principle to the prevention of eco-sensitive environment and ecology–denotes the economic value of ‘free air’.13 Recently, the National Green Tribunal (Principal Bench)14 has observed: “……[R]ight to life includes the right to a decent environment. The right to a clean environment is a guaranteed fundamental right. The courts could even impose exemplary damages against the polluter. Proper and healthy environment enables people to enjoy a quality of life which is the essence of the right guaranteed under Article 21. The right to have congenial environment for human existence is the right to life. The state has a duty in that behalf and to shed its extravagant unbridled sovereign power and to forge in its policy to maintain ecological balance and hygienic environment.” Deprivation of the elementary needs of a human being viz., food, water, health, education, job-opportunities, etc., in a welfare democratic state having welfare economy equates the unequal                                                              13 WILLIAM BOYES & MICHAEL MELVIN, TEXTBOOK OF ECONOMICS 7 (Biztantra, An Imprint of Dreamtech Press 6th ed. 2005). In fact, breathable air is becoming a luxury in many places. Consider the Opus Hotel in Vancouver, British Columbia. It is the first North American hotel to offer hand-held oxygen dispensers in every room. These oxygen canisters are small enough to fit into a purse or briefcase and hold enough air for twelve minutes of breathing time. Breathing oxygen is said to increase energy, improve cognitive performance, and reduce the effects of handovers. Opus charges $9.40 for the use of the canisters. 14 Judgment dated Feb. 6, 2014, (Swatanter Kumar, J.) in Court of its Own Motion v. State of H.P. & Ors., Application No. 237 (THC)/2013, CWPIL No. 15 of 2010, ¶ 15; Court of its Own Motion v. Union of India, JT 2012 Vol. 12 S.C. 503: The right to life is a right to live with dignity, safety and in a clean environment. Again in M/s Sterlite Industries Ltd. v. Tamil Nadu Pollution Control Board, 2013, Vol. I All India NGT Reporter, p. 368 it is held: “Article 21 of the Constitution of India which provides that no person shall be deprived of his right to life or personal liberty, except according to the procedure established by law, is interpreted by the Indian courts to include in this right to life, the right to clean and decent environment. Right to decent environment, as envisaged under Article 21 of the Constitution of India also gives, by necessary implication, the right against environmental degradation. It is in the form of right to protect the environment, as by protecting environment alone can we provide a decent and clean environment to the citizenry. Right to clean environment is a guaranteed fundamental right”. Bharati Law Review, Oct. – Dec., 2014 99     treatment to the common citizenry has been well established. So, the scission between the demands for the basic needs and the supply through the interstices of government agencies encourages the miscarriage of justice and enervate the human resources of the country as well. Fact that human life is composed of innumerable independent variables and dependent variable however, conglomeration of such homogeneous and heterogeneous demands musters towards the common choices in the society looking forward for the fulfillment of those. The interval between social choice and to the choice of the peoples’ representatives, steer the state machineries thus not only squandering the social wealth rather promoting scarcity of the resources and the appreciation of social costs of living thereof day by day. Good governance creates long-term values. Social and geo-political culture as well as the values play vital role in terms of sustainable development of a nation. The perceived consolidated democratic structure in India still hovers around the transition phase resulting in dwindling to collate the settled principles in macro- economic management of the natural resources, public administration and adequacy in institutionalized framework for better governance and its impact on the legal framework is no exception. Weal of the people is the social choice in a ‘welfare state’. Hence, in the event of improper distribution or restraint to equitable access to the elementary conditions of human life to its citizens squarely points out the disharmonious arrangements in distributive approaches of apparatus of the public agencies, committed to promote and cater out ‘justice–social, economic and political’. Distribution of both the benefits as well as burdens to the members for harmonizing the conflicting interests of the society peacefully entreats efficient performance of the legal mechanism of the country. “By ‘equitable’ I do not necessarily mean ethical or moral, but that which a given society considers to be appropriate to the need, status, and contribution of its various members. Appropriateness is shaped in part by principle and in part by precedent. It expresses what is reasonable and customary in a given distributive situation. To deviate from a rule that is founded on both reason and precedent would violate the stakeholders’ legitimate expectations, and this would be inequitable.”15 The close proximate relation between the good governance and economic performance for sustaining growth of the society is well established and becomes the growing understanding. The fast changing sustaining policies of the country have the impetus upon                                                              15 H. PEYTON YOUNG, EQUITY: IN THEORY AND PRACTICE 3 (Princeton University Press 1994). Bharati Law Review, Oct. – Dec., 2014 100     the distribution of the chances of lives of its citizens and such changes for who and what degree of sustainability are befitting to the needs of the mass myriad become the play-grounds of those trustees of the society who are battling to upkeep their status on a regular intervals. The transactions of development confined in the papers and the focus of the same in reality are one perfect illusion to the mass myriad. Hence, the noble approach ‘to encourage the peaceful expression of conflict, to promote tolerance and inclusiveness, build respect for diversity and promote responsible community practices.’16                                                              16 HANDBOOK ON RESTORATIVE JUSTICE PROGRAMMES 11 (Criminal Justice Handbook Series, United Nations, New York 2006, Sales No. E.06.V.15). work_7alkqks3ujbefil3aci4h4dpki ---- Climate justice, commons, and degrowth Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Ecological Economics journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/ecolecon Analysis Climate justice, commons, and degrowth Patricia E. (Ellie) Perkins Faculty of Environmental Studies, York University, Toronto, Ontario M3J 1P3, Canada A B S T R A C T Economic inequality reduces the political space for addressing climate change, by producing fear-based populism. Only when the safety, social status, and livelihoods of all members of society are assured will voluntary, democratic decisions be possible to reverse climate change and fairly mitigate its effects. Socio-environmental and climate justice, commoning, and decolonization are pre-conditions for participatory, responsible governance that both signals and assists the development of equitable socio-political systems. Degrowth movements, when they explicitly prioritize equity, can help to focus activism for climate justice and sustainable live- lihoods. This paper overviews the theoretical grounding for these arguments, drawing from the work of ecofeminist and Indigenous writers. Indigenous (and also ecofeminist) praxis is grounded in activists' leadership for commoning and resistance to extraction, the fossil fuel economy, and commodified property rights. These movements are building a politics of decolonization, respect, solidarity, and hope rather than xenophobia and despair. “The world is in the midst of a change in thinking about economic and social policy in general, and environmental policy in particular. Climate change is showing that the world depends upon a common pool resource, the atmosphere. Other common pool resources, such as fresh water and forests, are also important. Simply put, the world is discovering that people depend upon these common pool resources more than they be- lieved… How should people organize themselves when they depend upon a common pool resource? We need to study examples of peoples who have developed complex and productive systems using a common pool resource as the fundamental source of wealth.” – Ronald L. Trosper, Resilience, Reciprocity and Ecological Economics: Northwest Coast Sustainability (2009:4) 1. Introduction Climate change is an equity challenge. That is to say, it is a life-or- death challenge to human wisdom as evidenced in socio-political in- stitution-building.1 While there are large differences among countries (indicating that policies and institutions do matter), growing economic inequality within many countries since the 1980s – the same time period when climate change has become entrenched – has allowed a small elite, 1% of the global population, to become responsible for decisions about 82% of the world's wealth, including resource extraction, globalized production, investment, and energy production and use (Roser and Ortiz-Ospina, 2016; Oxfam, 2018). Meanwhile global income inequality is very high; half of humanity cannot afford basic food, shelter, education and healthcare (World Health Organization and World Bank, 2017; Roser, 2016). Even within most “emerging” and “rich” countries, a large seg- ment of the population feels disempowered and disrespected, to the point where populist leaders are elected, promising to restore dignity to the masses (Norrlof, 2018; Graves and Valpy, 2018a, 2018b). We are told that “over-consumption” is Anthropocene, inevitable, part of greedy human nature which “we” must struggle to get under control; we are told that sacrifices are necessary. Meanwhile factories close, carbon emissions and regressive taxes rise, economic inequality and insecurity deepen, workers riot in the streets, racism and fascism threaten. Economic growth nearly always heightens inequities, since in the absence of countervailing policies and institutions, wealth begets more wealth and political power in a positive-feedback cycle.2 The tendency under capitalism, state socialism, and colonialism for the powerful to keep coming out better off, and for exploitation of less-powerful people and of nature to accelerate, is the prime driver of climate change (Klein, 2014; Douthwaite, 1999; Korten, 2006; Latouche, 2003; Latouche, 2012; Wu, 2018; Whyte, 2018a). There are not enough negative feed- backs on this tendency of centralized colonial economies to keep https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ecolecon.2019.02.005 Received 28 February 2018; Received in revised form 7 February 2019; Accepted 7 February 2019 E-mail address: esperk@yorku.ca. 1 As Ostrom stated in her 2009 Nobel Economics lecture, “A core goal of public policy should be to facilitate the development of institutions that bring out the best in humans.” 2 This doesn't necessarily imply that degrowth on the contrary reduces inequities. Ecological Economics 160 (2019) 183–190 Available online 05 March 2019 0921-8009/ © 2019 Elsevier B.V. All rights reserved. T http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/journal/09218009 https://www.elsevier.com/locate/ecolecon https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ecolecon.2019.02.005 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ecolecon.2019.02.005 mailto:esperk@yorku.ca https://doi.org/10.1016/j.ecolecon.2019.02.005 http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1016/j.ecolecon.2019.02.005&domain=pdf growing, at the expense of “nature,” Indigenous land sovereignty, and marginalized people, for them to be either socially, politically, or eco- logically sustainable (see Thesis 2 in the Introduction to this issue).3 However, ecological destruction is not required by human nature – quite the contrary. There are many examples of human societies which have lived within ecosystem relationships for thousands of years. Common-pool resources, and other types of commons,4 have sustained human economies throughout human history. Collective governance systems that prevent privatization and thus maintain livelihoods for entire communities are increasingly recognized by climate justice ac- tivists and scholars as key to equitably meeting the challenges of cli- mate change. Indigenous scholars and activists critique private property in the context of settler colonialism, describing social-political-eco- nomic systems with sophisticated forms of property rights that have maintained human societies for thousands of years in a variety of en- vironments (Trosper, 2009; Borrows, 2010). Governance institutions which are central in these systems include those protecting reciprocal ecological relationships that foster collective continuance (Whyte, 2018b), contingent proprietorship and leadership (Trosper, 2009), ceremonial sharing, and social reciprocity demonstrated through po- tlatches and other rituals (Trosper, 2009; Atleo, 2011). While they have survived, all of these collective governance institutions have been threatened and nearly destroyed by colonialism. Ecofeminist theorists describe how the rise of capitalism and colo- nialism led to destruction of previously-existing commons, undermined women's rights, and produced widespread social inequity and margin- alization (Federici, 2014, 2018; Mies, 1986/1999; Mies and Bennholdt- Thomsen, 2001). These global and local histories underlie economic, environmental and climate injustice today. In the context of climate change, through a wide range of movements and initiatives – many led by Indigenous people and/or by women – they are beginning to be acknowledged and redressed. This paper's argument is that equity, decolonization, and activism are central to building political institutions to reduce carbon emissions and material throughput in human economies, so that humans can again flourish within reciprocal relationships with the rest of life. Climate justice is not only important in its own right, for moral/ethical reasons, but is also key to the politics of addressing climate change. The degrowth movement, which provides a catalyst for activism because it highlights the problems of and solutions to material throughput and over-consumption in rich countries, sometimes under- emphasizes equity and the unfair impacts of shrinking GDP on parti- cular people and geographic areas. However, with equity foremost, degrowth helps to redefine activist goals, because as (re)commoning takes place, growth itself is less relevant than provisioning – which happens both within and outside of the measured/recognized market, economy, and governance structures (Dengler and Seebacher, 2018). Degrowth thus helps blur old categories and ideals, and focus on new, more relevant ones in times of climate crisis. The sections of this paper, which take up each of these points, are meant as an overview and entry point into huge literatures on all of the issues mentioned. Following a section on ecofeminism, commons, cli- mate justice, and degrowth, in the next section Indigenous leadership and literatures on climate justice and commons are discussed briefly. The conclusion returns to the political role of equity in addressing cli- mate change, and to the synergies between ecofeminist and Indigenous analyses. 2. Ecofeminism, commons, climate justice, and degrowth The call of ecofeminists5 for recognition of collective, unpaid, taken- for-granted foundational contributions of “nature” and “women's work” to socio-economic processes, and the patriarchal exploitation involved, highlights the importance of redistribution and common, shared pro- visioning in human societies (Mellor, 1997a; Mies, 1986/1999; Salleh, 2009). As Carol Rose pointed out decades ago, commons of many kinds are ‘hidden in plain sight.’ Commons such as oceans and watersheds, the Earth's atmosphere, the internet, and languages, are ubiquitous (Hess, 2008); they remain foundational supports for societies and economies, just like unpaid work and ‘nature;’ and they also act as flywheels, maintaining and undergirding otherwise-unsustainable economic sys- tems. Unpaid work and the vital economic role of ecological systems are all much larger than the economy that non-Indigenous people have learned to ‘see’ (Gibson-Graham, 2006; Williams, 2005; Fournier, 2013, UNDP, 2015). The ‘first enclosure’ of the commons in 16th-century Europe and its colonies was fundamental to both the establishment of capitalism and the deepening of patriarchy (Federici, 2014:68–75). Women, who “suffered most when the land was lost and the village community fell apart” (Ibid. 73), actively fought to protect the commons; “women holding pitchforks and scythes resisted the fencing of the land or the draining of the fens when their livelihood was threatened” (Ibid.). The European enclosures led to social crisis, misogyny and violence against women, reducing their employment options and confining them to the home and unpaid reproductive work. In this transition from feudalism to capitalism, “women suffered a unique process of social degradation that was fundamental to the accumulation of capital and has remained so ever since” (Ibid. 75). Meanwhile, in the colonies, where European conquests imposed the same exploitative systems, women's resistance to enclosures preserved traditional commons-based religions and cultural practices. In Latin America, women “directed or counseled all the great anti-colonial revolts” (Ibid., 232, quoting De Leon, 1985, vol. 1:76). Commons are still more prevalent and more important in assuring people's livelihoods globally than many may realize. “Worldwide the International Land Alliance estimates that there are an estimated 2 billion people whose lives revolve around subsistence commons of forest, fisheries, arable land, water and wild game” (Bollier and Weston, 2014:1). Those dependent on commons are often the most margin- alized. Mutual aid, utopian communities, and grassroots collaborative economic initiatives have allowed Black Americans to persevere in 3 In traditional justice terminology, climate justice involves the principles of distributional and procedural justice (fairness in how material goods are dis- tributed among people, and in political access by all people), as well as inter- generational justice (meaning that current human consumption doesn't endanger the welfare of future generations). Carrying equity principles a bit further re- quires including interspecies justice (human respect for other species' welfare and continued existence/non-extinction) and intersectional justice (measures to counteract multifaceted vulnerability and marginalization). Restorative justice implies reshaping human institutions not only for redress but also so that so- ciety can self-correct, reinvigorate itself, and prevent inequitable outcomes from occurring. Distributional justice involves material equity; all the other types of justice mentioned above go beyond the material to extend equity principles into dynamic realms of governance, time, race, class, gender and more-than-human species (see Thesis 1 and Thesis 3 in the Introduction to this Special Issue). 4 Following Turner and Brownhill (2001), in this paper the word ‘commons’ means organized ways of providing the essentials of life to all. Examples include language, health care, regulated clean air and water, universal education, open environmental spaces and forests, nutritious food, adequate shelter, and equi- table political governance. Charlotte Hess, another commons researcher, uses this definition: “A commons is a resource shared by a group where the resource is vulnerable to enclosure, overuse and social dilemmas. Unlike a public good, it requires management and protection in order to sustain it” (Hess, 2008:37). 5 There are many variants of ecofeminism, but all critique the undervaluation and exploitation of women and nature (Plumwood, 1993; Warren, 2000; Gaard and Gruen, 1993, Gaard, 2011, Merchant, 1980, Mellor, 1997a; Salleh, 1997; Mies and Shiva, 2014). Feminist theory in general emphasizes justice, respect for diversity and pluralism, critiques of power and wealth concentration, and the central importance of biological/ecological processes (Spencer et al., 2018). P.E.E. Perkins Ecological Economics 160 (2019) 183–190 184 “finding alternative economic strategies to promote economic stability and economic independence in the face of fierce competition, racial discrimination, and White supremacist violence and sabotage” while building leadership and community stability (Gordon Nembhard, 2014:27). Institutional economists such as Douglass North “have long con- tended that property rights lie at the core of the economic growth that has dominated the last 300 years of world history” (Evans, 2005:86), which is to say that the ‘first enclosure’ of the commons made possible the exponential growth of agrarian and then industrial capitalist economies. The gendered marginalization and misery noted above was a direct result of the economic growth which depended on commodi- fying and privatizing formerly-communal land. But as long ago as the fourth century BC, “state-defined property was individual, male, and private – a relation which individuals held with the State, not with each other. Collective or communal tenure was, in contrast, described by Plato as ‘natural;’ its relations were controlled by, and internal to, a self- defining community…. By the 20th century… (w)hether ideology was communist, socialist, nationalist, or capitalist, a dominant shared strategy… was that community-based tenure (or customary tenure as usually known) must be extinguished in the interests of progress” (Wily, 2018:2). Traditional common-pool resources and common property have a formal or informal system of property rights, and enforced governance that effectively allows those with shared access to protect the commons from outsiders. Common property allocates certain rights to members of a group: access, extraction, management, exclusion, and/or alienation rights (Hess, 2008:34). “New commons” include a wide range of types of connections between groups of humans and natural resources, goods, property, or cultural assets: “The new commons literature focuses on collective action, voluntary associations, and collaboration. While property rights and the nature of the good may still be important, there is a growing emphasis on questions of governance, participatory pro- cesses, and trust; and there is a groundswell of interest in shared values and moral responsibility” (Hess, 2008:37). Even traditional commons such as communally-held land are surprisingly resilient, widespread, and growing in places – due in some cases to the progress of Indigenous peoples in gaining recognition for their communal land rights (Wily, 2018). Neoclassical economists have begun to investigate the reasons why communal tenure can be more efficient than private property: “When the output produced with the asset is a public good, then communal property rights (joint ownership) may sometimes be op- timal” (Besley and Ghatak, 2010:4552). In the face of climate change, movements in the Global South and North, largely led by women, are resisting ongoing enclosures for ex- traction and fossil fuel industries and, in the process, reclaiming com- mons. “To the extent that the capitalist energy system is seized and redirected towards commoning, actors within it have reduced dan- gerous emissions and elaborated an alternative system premised on sustainable energy…. This ‘actually existing’ movement of commoners is the result of the exploited taking over some of the organizations of capital and using them to (a) undermine profit and at the same time (b) negotiate and construct means for satisfying universal needs” (Brownhill and Turner, 2008:16; see also Akbulut, 2017). For example, La Via Campesina's Declaration at the 2015 International Forum for Agroecology stated, “Collective rights and ac- cess to the commons are a fundamental pillar of agroecology. We share access to territories that are the home to many different peer groups, and we have sophisticated customary systems for regulating access and avoiding conflicts that we want to preserve and to strengthen” (Giacomini, 2016:98). La Via Campesina also notes, “As savers of seed and living libraries of knowledge about local biodiversity and food systems, women are often more closely connected to the commons than men” (Ibid). Necessary steps in the process of re-commoning include “defending and reclaiming of public space, and opposition to further privatization of common resources and spaces; … (localized) production, exchange, and consumption; … decentralization; reciprocity (instead of) me- chanical mass solidarity; … policy from below, as a living process, in- stead of policy from above; … (and) manifold ways of realizing a community and a multiplicity of communities” (Mies and Bennholdt- Thomsen, 2001:1021–1022). In principle, degrowth and commoning movements seem like nat- ural allies. They arise in opposition to crushing centralization and globalization, income and power concentration, and destruction of local communities; they are fundamentally democratic and relationship- based; their stance is critical of “sustainable development,” counter- hegemonic, and anti-capitalist. But in my view, topics such as women, gender, intersectionality, Indigenous peoples, colonialism, and im- plications for the marginalized remain underexplored in degrowth analysis (Deschner and Hurst, 2018). There are exceptions, and a few authors call for venues or discussions or shared political platforms to bring together different perspectives (e.g. Martinez-Alier et al., 2010:1746, Martinez-Alier, 2012; Bonaiuti, 2012; Asara et al., 2015). (Re)commoning opens an ethical, political, and currently relevant means to motivate and cushion degrowth, broaden its appeal, and emphasize its practical/livelihood applications, in recognition of the tremendous potential that degrowth has to negatively affect margin- alized people whose precarious lifeways imply minimal ability to handle shocks and disruption (D'Alisa et al., 2014). What steps might this entail? The degrowth movement has not (yet?) seriously considered or addressed the long-standing feminist and ecofeminist literatures regarding the extent to which the measured/ growth economy depends upon unpaid work, mostly done by women, and unpaid ecological services. Many degrowth authors seem blind to the effects of patriarchy, gender violence, colonialism, and wage dis- crimination in forcing certain members of humanity, and “nature” (c.f. Francis Bacon – see Merchant, 2008), to continue providing other members of humanity the means to support their well-being. Degrowth theorist Takis Fotopoulos points out that degrowth ad- dresses the ecological crisis while essentially ignoring the political, social, economic, and class crises (Fotopoulos, 2007:5). This is a pro- blem, he says: “The crucial issue today is how we may create a new society where institutionalized domination of human being over human being and the consequent idea of dominating nature are ruled out” (2007:8). Fotopoulos shows how both socialist and capitalist growth depend fundamentally on income concentration – both materially and environmentally – since industrialization depends on privatization of the means of production and division of labour; it is simply not possible for the benefits of increased production to be universalized because this would endanger the conditions of income disparity required by profit maximization. “Progress, in the sense of improvements in welfare through economic growth, has a necessarily non-universal character. Therefore, the moment of truth for the present social system will come, when it will be universally acknowledged that the very existence of the present wasteful consumption standards depends on the fact that only a small proportion of the world population, now or in the future, are able to enjoy them” (2007:14–15). He thus provides the reason why de- growth cannot prioritize redistribution OR gender equity without what he calls a “cultural revolution,” the “transformation of existing in- stitutions” – but this must be accomplished without alienating “the lower social groups (including the lower middle class), which would particularly have to pay the price for the adoption of the measures involved” if they are carried out within the market system by inter- nalizing externalities (2007: 18). “Progress,” as Maria Mies noted in 1986, depends not just on global income inequality but on patriarchy, and on disguising women's eco- nomic interests even from themselves. For society to vote democrati- cally for degrowth, these fundamental characteristics of prevailing economic systems would need to be maintained. Fotopoulos hints at the extensive changes which would be necessary to bring this exploitation to light when he says, “To my mind, it is only through a transitional P.E.E. Perkins Ecological Economics 160 (2019) 183–190 185 strategy aiming to create new democratic political and economic in- stitutions and, through paideia, which would aim to make hegemonic the corresponding values, that we could realistically hope to create the conditions for the emergence of an economy and society not based on economic growth: a real ecological democracy, as an integral part of an Inclusive Democracy” (2007:19). The word paideia, meaning “child- rearing and education,” gives away the deep ecofeminist content of his remarks: child-rearing and education, currently taken for granted, not worthy of comment, and done largely for free almost exclusively by women, are the key to transforming society so that people can generally see that growth is not the point; ongoing livelihood and quality of life for all is. What will induce the emergent “new forms of economic and social organization” (Bonaiuti, 2012) to be good from an ecofeminist per- spective – that is, equitable for women and all marginalized ‘others’, and for more-than-human life/“nature”? The answer to this question is the crux of climate-crisis-driven system change. From the standpoint of equity/redistribution and ecological bal- ance, degrowth thus can seem a rather tangential tactic. Because some degrowth theorists focus mainly on reducing humans' energy use and material throughput, the degrowth movement they envision can seem somewhat conflicted and unclear about its equity implications. Degrowth activists generally maintain that they want degrowth with equity, but the movement itself to date largely lacks participation and input from marginalized workers from either the global North or the global South, who might be able to represent and integrate those con- cerns – if indeed this is possible (see Thesis 4 in the Introduction to this issue). Other degrowth proponents define their goals in terms of re- organizing the social metabolism towards socially-determined aims, once growth itself is decentred as a societal indicator of progress (Kallis and March, 2014). Turner et al., 2012 article in a special issue of Capitalism Nature Socialism on degrowth, substitute ‘de-alienation’ in Marxian terms as a better focus than degrowth, since this incorporates both justice AND ecology. Justice, because all workers share the alienation which flows from over-consumption and overwork, and this shared burden provides a basis for political action, and for economic restructuring with equity. Ecology, because commons are an age-old solution evolved by humans to meet the challenges of joint sustenance, risk, and long-term en- vironmental equilibrium. In terms of social justice, given the ever-present reality that eco- nomic contraction (or changes of any kind) tend to impact most gravely on people who are already marginalized, most degrowth theorists specify that attention to justice is crucial in bringing about degrowth, and they try to include voices from the margins in arguing for the de- growth agenda. Part of this strategy includes pointing out that growth too hurts the poor, due to its ecological, climate change, and neoliberal social impacts. Martinez-Alier, a central figure in the degrowth move- ment, argues in his book The Environmentalism of the Poor (2002) that strategies used by poor people worldwide to minimize or buffer the environmental consequences of economic growth, which fall heavily on them and endanger their more sustainable livelihoods, effectively shrink the size of the measured, growth-focused economy. Nonetheless, from an ecofeminist and equity-driven perspective, it seems dangerous to advocate degrowth without very clear and specific corollary measures to negate the tendency of the powerful to come out better-off. Traditional income redistribution mechanisms usually rely at least theoretically on growth, so that the least well-off can gradually be al- located a proportionally larger share of economic returns without others having to receive absolutely less. In practice, growth is usually accompanied by increases in both economic and political inequity, and worsening income distribution (Piketty, 2014; Wilkinson and Pickett, 2009). But what mechanism can address historically-based material inequities, both within and among countries and regions, as well as globally? Without growth as the engine, in reality as well as in theory, what can drive progressive North-South redistribution? Economic lo- calization and decentralization can lead to greater equity in specific cases (Kaufman, 2012; Gibson-Graham, 2006; Rowan, 2019) but the post-colonial/decolonizing global distribution questions remain (Dengler and Seebacher, 2018, 2019; Lang, 2017; Paulsen, 2017). This remains an under-developed area of degrowth theory. Since degrowth involves substituting social benefits which are not derived from material throughput in the economy for economic benefits which are materially-dependent, it is centrally concerned with issues like unpaid work, caring, community as differentiated from individual welfare, and other such matters which feminist economists have studied for decades. Ecofeminists, in particular, have long considered these is- sues (Mellor, 1997b, Mellor, 1992, Kuiper and Perkins, 2005, Shiva, 1988, Mies and Shiva and Mies, 1993). Undervalued economic factors include women's work (and indeed all under- and unpaid work), as well as non-monetized services and material inputs from ‘nature’ and colonial theft which are incorporated into the economic sphere virtually for free. Whenever they are esti- mated – e.g. Costanza et al. (1997, 2014), Pietilä (1997); D'Alisa and Cattaneo (2013); UNDP (2015) – these unpaid or ‘free’ services and goods generally dwarf the measured economy in value, yet they are usually not central to policy deliberations and they are often ignored entirely. Women's work and “nature” are crucial and irreplaceable foundations of the measured economy. Maria Mies has shown how capitalism was founded and continues to depend for its existence on the unpaid and underpaid work of women; Mary Mellor and Ariel Salleh and many other theorists have traced the material links between wo- men's work and what economists call “ecosystem services”; these issues of underpayment and inequality based in social injustice and environ- mental depredation, and the predictable ways in which they create economic winners and losers, are grounded in colonialism, patriarchy, under-development, and race and class discrimination both within countries and globally. Just as the ‘jobs vs. environment’ conflicts of 20 years ago are being superseded via ‘green jobs’ and ‘green community development’ movements which recognize the importance of safe green sustainable jobs for all workers, as the climate crisis intensifies ‘degrowth vs. re- distribution’ conflicts will need to be overcome through ‘de-alienation via commoning,’ which lays the groundwork for all members of society to be supported, simply, first and foremost, so that growth becomes irrelevant (Macgregor, 2014). This focus on participatory commons governance decenters both growth and degrowth as goals: Degrowth is mostly a means to an end, which is a just, peaceful quality of life for all. In comparison with current realities, income redistribution is more central than degrowth per se as a step in a good direction. More progressive wealth taxation policy including inheritance taxes and ceilings that favour wealth dis- tribution; crackdowns on tax havens and tax flight; and anti-corruption policies in general are examples of ways to advocate and move towards this goal even within capitalism and current political structures, by building political will for transparency and redistribution. More fun- damental reconstruction of commons in the Western/European domi- nated world, however, will involve deep restructuring of economic systems, livelihoods, rights, and culture (Fuente Carrasco et al., 2019; Whyte, 2017a, 2017b, 2018a). Colonialism, as noted above, violently suppressed and continues to undermine Indigenous socio-economic institutions that exemplify commons governance for securing sustainable livelihoods. Is it possible for ecofeminist, degrowth, and Indigenous activists to become allies in re-commoning? Says Indigenous writer Lindsay Nixon: “Indigenous feminists know that mainstream feminism predominantly represents white settler feminists who, more often than not, choose to ignore the ongoing processes of colonialism from which they actually benefit…. Ecofeminism that appropriates Indigenous environmental P.E.E. Perkins Ecological Economics 160 (2019) 183–190 186 knowledges often fails to fully represent what environmental justice means to Indigenous communities. What is often ignored within these analyses is how neocolonial state violence, compounded by exposure to environmental contaminants, is embodied in very specific ways for Indigenous women and Two-Spirit peoples…. Indigenous peoples have again and again described how solutions to the effects of environmental contamination need to extend far beyond the return of land…. If eco- feminists truly want to engage with Indigenous feminism to legitimize their own movements, they must first engage with their own positionality and privilege as settlers: a positionality on which the continuation of settler-colonialism and the ongoing genocide of Indigenous peoples are prefaced. Furthermore, Indigenous peoples don't need saviour feminists defining what strategies must be used to address environmental con- tamination within Indigenous communities…. What Indigenous feminists want from eco-feminists is simple: Sit down, be quiet, and listen” (Nixon, 2015) This call to listen respectfully is consistent with an empirical, evi- dence-based approach to sustainable livelihoods, as pointed out by Ronald Trosper in the quotation that heads this paper (Trosper, 2009:4). 3. Indigenous commons, climate justice, and degrowth Sustainable ecological practices, communal wealth-sharing, and institutions that preserve long-term quality of life are apparent in many Indigenous governance systems. In Canada and elsewhere, Indigenous leadership, especially by young women, is generating a new impetus for settler-allies to learn about and act on these lifeways and the history and pernicious legacies of colonialism. International legal scholar Shawkat Alam notes, “Collective rights are often affiliated with Indigenous people, as they are defined as rights held by groups…. However, it has been argued that the ‘recognition of collectivities and collective rights is one of the most contested in in- ternational law and politics’. Indeed… this concept of collective rights can be seen to conflict with Western ideas of individual freedom and liberty…. Collective rights have been seen to foster tolerance, and di- versity of culture and knowledge. To this end, many Indigenous peoples view the recognition of their cultural rights as ‘of paramount im- portance’ or ‘as a token of respect towards their identity and commu- nities as well as the only way for their survival and development’” (Alam, 2012:588; Xanthaki, 2007:13). Indigenous legal scholar John Borrows has demonstrated the extent to which First Nations governance traditions have provided a founda- tion for current Canadian law, as part of a living, resilient legal system which ‘works’ in the modern world (Borrows, 2010). Carol Rose, in a very thorough 1986 study, demonstrated that the legal status of com- mons is well-represented, understood and respected in modern Western legal traditions, and in fact that there are so many types and advantages of collective property rights that their benefits remain unambiguous; “the commons was not tragic, but comedic, in the sense of a story with a happy outcome” (Rose, 1986:723). The Iroquois or Haudenosaunee confederacy among the Seneca, Cayuga, Onondaga, Oneida, Mohawk, and Tuscarora peoples was “probably the greatest Indigenous polity north of the Rio Grande in the two centuries before Columbus and definitely the greatest in the two centuries after” (Mann, 2005:330). The Haudenosaunee ‘Great Law of Peace,’ with its 117 codicils setting out ways of achieving political balance, requiring subsidiarity, and setting checks on authority, has been cited as the direct inspiration for the U.S. Constitution (Ibid.:333). However, while they adopted Haudenosaunee protections for liberty and individual rights going far beyond European standards of the time, the U.S. constitutional ‘framers’ failed to incorporate Haudenosaunee traditions of communal property ownership (Ibid.: 333–336). Arguably, they thus missed out on a crucial piece of the overall system's tradi- tional, well-evolved constraints on individual wealth-accumulation and, thus, political power – given the U.S. colonial governance system's lack of negative feedbacks on wealth accumulation, unlike Indigenous governance systems. Indigenous histories document a diversity of ways of organizing society to prioritize resilience, interdependence, and ecological re- lationships (Trosper, 2009; Leroy, 2016). Indigenous traditions of hospitality, sharing, potlatch (or giving away material wealth to de- monstrate moral and community standing), humility, and reverence for the earth and all its creatures and life systems are central to locally- appropriate commons governance processes. First Nations also had nested governance institutions which seem to correspond with what Elinor Ostrom has cited as successful ‘polycentric’ ways to govern large- scale commons (Ostrom, 2009a, 2010, 2014). The active suppression of the potlatch by the Canadian government between 1884 and 1951, on penalty of 2 to 6 month jail terms, shows the extent to which gift-giving, generosity, and moral community re- lationships were inimical to the selfishness and violence of colonial capitalist expansionism. During the potlatch, guests are named and given gifts with the words, “you are recognized.” In The Principles of Tsawalk: An Indigenous Approach to Global Crisis, E. Richard Atleo (Umeek) says, “Over time it was learned that gift giving and recognition promoted balance and harmony between beings, that (this) obeyed what might be called the laws of the positive side of polarity…. When two neighbouring nations shared the same resources, whether cedar, salmon, or human, then it was obvious to the ancient Nuu-chah-nulth that to neglect the act of recognition would open the way to conflict, while to observe the act of recognition, through what I refer to as ‘mutual concern,’ would open the way to balance and harmony.” (Atleo, 2011, pp. 80–81) Indigenous forms of resource management prior to colonization included burning forests to create grasslands for common hunting grounds and areas where food plants and medicinal herbs could be harvested by visitors of many nations (First Story, 2016; Frost, 2019; Turner et al., 2000); Shasta and Hupa management of salmon fisheries through a combination of ritual, ceremony, taboos, respect for elders, and astute observation of the fish over many years (Berkes and Folke, 2002:126–127); Cree oral history to transmit knowledge of long-term cycles in caribou herd fluctuations (Ibid.:140); and Nishinaabeg myths and stories to convey knowledge about interrelated natural phenomena, along with human dependence and humility (Simpson, 2011:18). All these practices depend upon shared cultures, resource use by groups for the benefit of the whole collectivity, and limitations not just on in- dividual consumption and wealth accumulation but on overall human consumption when necessary to preserve the natural resource – in other words, effective and sustainable commons governance. Balanced gender roles and social domains (e.g. Haudenosaunee women were clan heads; they chose the male sachems or chiefs) were and are the norm in many Indigenous societies (Mann, 2005:372–373). Indigenous women, as those responsible for water and life-transmission, lead the most powerful grassroots environmental movements in Canada today (Perkins, 2017; Temper, 2018b). Indigenous chief and activist Arthur Manuel and R.M. Derrickson comment in their book Unsettling Canada: A National Wake-Up Call that women have long held leading roles in Indigenous activism on land, rights and the environment, and the majority of young Indigenous activists today are women (Manuel and Derrickson, 2015:211). Indigenous authors have pointed out that, besides gendered economic and social roles in a patriarchal society, cultural factors also lead Indigenous women to assert their voices and leadership on matters related to water, health, education and liveli- hoods (Gorecki, 2014; Nixon, 2015; Awadalia et al., 2015; Ellis, 2015; Whyte, 2014a). The links between exploitation of land, resources, and women are clear: “…Indigenous women activists and academics have shown how the foundation of contemporary capitalism was contingent on industrial P.E.E. Perkins Ecological Economics 160 (2019) 183–190 187 resource extraction of Indigenous people's land, which was also si- multaneously fully reliant on disempowering any positive ethic towards nature and women. This was achieved by installing European forms of gender relations and dismantling women's power, aided by the appro- priation of Indigenous women's bodies. Residential schools were per- haps the strongest tools in reinscribing balanced gender relations of North American Indigenous matrilocal societies into the unequal ones of patriarchal models imposed by European colonizers and settlers…. (T)he centrality of resisting the colonization of Mother Earth, Terra Madre, and Pachamama is paramount” (Gorecki, 2014).6 As noted by climate justice activists, it is those on the front lines of climate change – both extreme weather events and extraction – who are most aware of its impacts and most knowledgeable about how they should be addressed; this puts women at the forefront of climate justice struggles (Beuchler and Hanson, 2015:228). Indigenous women, facing multiple health and livelihood crises, are leading powerful movements to address this issue at its source (Whyte, 2014a; Whyte, 2017a, 2017b; Green, 2017; Temper, 2018a). Commoning, or reclaiming/rebuilding Indigenous governance sys- tems, requires decolonization. Dene activist Glen Coulthard, in his book Red Skin White Masks, discusses the hope and the promise of commons: “What must be recognized by those inclined to advocate a blanket ‘return to the commons’ as a redistributive counterstrategy to the neoliberal state's new round of enclosures, is that, in liberal settler states such as Canada, the ‘commons’ not only belong to somebody – the First Peoples of this land – they also deeply inform and sustain Indigenous modes of thought and behaviour that harbour profound insights into the main- tenance of relationships within and between human beings and the nat- ural world built on principles of reciprocity, nonexploitation and re- spectful coexistence. By ignoring or downplaying the injustice of colonial dispossession, critical theory and left political strategy not only risks becoming complicit in the very structures and processes of domination that it ought to oppose, but it also risks overlooking what could prove to be invaluable glimpses into the ethical practices and preconditions re- quired for the construction of a more just and sustainable world order” (Coulthard, 2014:12) Justice-oriented economic transformation requires non-Indigenous people to undertake significant and ongoing education about the da- mage and legacies of colonialism in order to begin to build economic institutions that respect the contributions and rights of women and Indigenous peoples, both individually and collectively (Davis, 2010; Tuck, 2017; Fortier, 2017; Davis and Todd, 2016; Whyte, 2016). In- digenous governance systems underscore how foundational justice is for long-lived and ecologically-sustainable commons. However, de- growth theorists and activists have yet to engage much with this, or with Indigenous activists and approaches in North America; the Eur- opean degrowth movement even less so. Global commoning movements grounded in Indigenous lifeways, including Buen Vivir, Pachakuti, and Sumak Kawsay in Latin America, Ecological Swaraj in India, Gross National Happiness in Bhutan, Ubuntu in Africa, and Maori “Economy of Mana” in New Zealand, have many parallels with degrowth, especially their insistence on transformative reorganization of society to recenter harmony among humans and with the more-than-human world, as some degrowth writers point out (Kothari et al., 2014; Garcia, 2012; Gudynas, 2015; Thomson, 2010; Della Valle, 2017; Meynen, 2016; Hoeft, 2018; Martinez-Alier, 2012; Latouche, 2007; Escobar, 2015; Foster, 2011; Verma, 2017). 4. Conclusion: equity, commons, and climate justice Women's movements, and especially Indigenous women's move- ments, revive and underscore the importance of participatory democ- racy and local responsibility for preventing the commodification of water, mineral resources, forests, fisheries, information, collective transportation, and other widely shared systems that are vitally im- portant for most communities' livelihoods and for human flourishing (Bollier and Weston, 2013; Murota and Takeshita, 2013; Shimada, 2010; Dyer-Witheford, 2011; Cochrane, 2014; Hess and Ostrom, 2007; Great Lakes Commons, 2013). The toxic effects of fossil fuel and other extraction, and industrial production more generally – water and air pollution, ecosystem impacts on fish, wildlife, soils, agriculture, etc., trampling on local governance processes, Indigenous land rights, and the health of the most vulnerable – first and most clearly demonstrate the deathly problematic nature of the economic system that produces climate change. The impacts of fossil fuel consumption – greenhouse gas emissions leading to extreme weather events, weather variability, etc. – while global in their im- plications, are longer-incubating but also crucially important in per- petuating climate change. In both production and consumption, roles and impacts are gendered (Cohen, 2017) and environmental injustices abound. Climate justice includes both production and consumption related activism. This paper presents an alternative, deeper argument regarding a way forward in times of worsening inequality and climate chaos: that humans have proven themselves to be capable of building socio-cultural systems which secure a respected place for all members of society and provide for their livelihoods, material needs and emotional welfare through commons, protected by collective social governance institu- tions. Despite centuries of colonialism, imperialism, and capitalist growth, such commons continue to sustain and supplement the liveli- hoods of most people in the world. Led by the marginalized, who are well aware of this, commoning is a mode of social activism which al- lows people to relink with the means to collectively control production themselves, outside of the market and independent of capital (Fournier, 2013). Commoning implies addressing all forms of justice: distributional, procedural, intergenerational, intersectional, interspecies, restorative. It also requires understanding the deep colonial roots of growth itself, in order to actively “unsettle” the collaborative process of redressing wrongs, building respect and humility, and envisioning a resilient, sustainable future. Relationships between settler ecofeminists, Indigenous women activists, and global climate justice movements re- quire settlers to commit to ongoing self-education, respect, and soli- darity in working towards decolonization. Equity-oriented degrowth, climate justice, and commoning are thus potentially mutually reinforcing, and offer a politically viable path to- wards energy transition and a post-capitalist future. The first step along this path is to dismantle colonialism, restore stolen land to its Indigenous caretakers in reconciliation, and (re)build the social respect, relationships and fundamental human values that can link all members of society together, without fear or xenophobia, for shared and re- sponsible commons governance. References Akbulut, B., 2017. Carework as Commons: Toward a Feminist Degrowth Agenda. Resilience (February 2). http://www.resilience.org/stories/2017-02-02/carework- as-commons-towards-a-feminist-degrowth-agenda/. Alam, S., 2012. Collective indigenous rights and the environment. In: Alam, S., Bhuiyan, J.H., Chowdhury, T.M., Techera, E.J. (Eds.), Routledge Handbook of International Environmental Law. Routledge, New York, pp. 585–602. Asara, V., Otero, I., Demaria, F., Corbera, Ed, 2015. Socially sustainable edgrowth as a social-ecological transformation: repoliticizing sustainability. Sustain. Sci. 10 (3), 375–384. Atleo, E.R. (Emeek), 2011. Principles of Tsawalk: An Indigenous Approach to Global Crisis. UBC Press, Vancouver. 6 Canada's ongoing crisis of more than 1200 Missing and Murdered Indigenous Women and Girls since 1980 shows that the deadly connections among capitalism, colonialism, resource extraction, ecological destruction, patriarchy, gendered violence, and racism continue (Kirkup, 2016; Inter- American Commission on Human Rights, 2014; Narine, 2015; Women's Earth Alliance and Native Youth Sexual Health Network, 2016; Green, 2017). P.E.E. Perkins Ecological Economics 160 (2019) 183–190 188 http://www.resilience.org/stories/2017-02-02/carework-as-commons-towards-a-feminist-degrowth-agenda/ http://www.resilience.org/stories/2017-02-02/carework-as-commons-towards-a-feminist-degrowth-agenda/ http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0010 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0010 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0010 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0015 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0015 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0015 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0020 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0020 Awadalia, C., Coutinho-Sledge, P., Criscitiello, A., Gorecki, J., Sapra, S., 2015. Climate Change and Feminist Environmentalisms: Closing Remarks. FeministWire (May 1). http://www.thefeministwire.com/2015/05/climate-change-and-feminist- environmentalisms-closing-remarks/. Berkes, F., Folke, C., 2002. Back to the future: ecosystem dynamics and local knowledge. In: Gunderson, L.H., Holling, C.S. (Eds.), Panarchy: Understanding Transformations in Human and Natural Systems. Island Press, Washington, DC/Covelo, CA/London, UK, pp. 121–146. Besley, T., Ghatak, M., 2010. Property rights and economic development. In: Rodrik, D., Rosenzweig, M. (Eds.), Handbook of Development Economics. vol. 5. pp. 4535–4595. ch. 68. http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/25428/1/property_rights_and_ economic_development.pdf. Beuchler, S., Hanson, A., 2015. A Political Ecology of Women, Water, and Global Environmental Change. Routledge, New York/London. Bollier, D., Weston, B., 2013. Green Governance: Ecological Survival, Human Rights, and the Law of the Commons. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Bollier, D., Weston, B., 2014. The Commons as a Growing Global Movement. CSRwire Talkback (Jan. 31). http://www.csrwire.com/blog/posts/1203-the-commons-as-a- growing-global-movement. Bonaiuti, M., 2012. Degrowth: tools for a complex analysis of the multidimensional crisis. Capital. Nat. Social. 23 (1), 30–50. Borrows, J., 2010. Canada's Indigenous Constitution. University of Toronto Press, Toronto. Brownhill, L., Turner, T., 2008. Commoners against Climate Change. Europe Solidaire sans Frontières. http://www.europe-solidaire.org/spip.php?article9416. Cochrane, Regina, 2014. Climate change, Buen Vivir, and the dialectic of enlightenment: toward a feminist critical philosophy of climate justice. Hypatia 29 (3), 577–598. Cohen, M.G., 2017. Climate Change and Gender in Rich Countries: Work, Public Policy and Action. Routledge, London/New York. Costanza, R., et al., 1997. The value of the world's ecosystem services and natural capital. Nature 387, 253–260. Costanza, R., de Groot, R., Sutton, P., van der Ploeg, S., Anderson, S.J., Kubiszewski, I., Farber, S., Turner, R.K., 2014. Changes in the global value of ecosystem services. Glob. Environ. Chang. 26, 152–158. Coulthard, G.S., 2014. Red Skin White Masks: Rejecting the Colonial Politics of Recognition. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis. D'Alisa, G., Cattaneo, C., 2013. Household work and energy consumption: a degrowth perspective. Catalonia's case study. J. Clean. Prod. 38, 71–79. D'Alisa, G., Demaria, F., Kallis, G., 2014. Degrowth: A Vocabulary for a New Era. Routledge, London/New York. Davis, L. (Ed.), 2010. Alliances: Re/Envisioning Indigenous-non-Indigenous Relationships. University of Toronto Press, Toronto. Davis, H., Todd, Z., 2016. On the importance of a date, or decolonizing the Anthropocene. ACME Int. J. Crit. Geogr. 16 (4), 761–780. De Leon, A.G., 1985. Resistencia y Utopia. vols. 1 and 2 Ediciones Era, México, DF. Della Valle, P., 2017. Indigenous degrowth and global capitalism: exploring notions of development in New Zealand literature. In: Ramsey-Kurtz, H., Kennedy, M. (Eds.), Uncommon Wealths in Postcolonial Fiction. Brill, Leiden, pp. 207–225. Dengler, C., Seebacher, L.M., 2018. Growth Pessimism, but Degrowth Optimism. Social Europe (17 December). https://www.socialeurope.eu/growth-pessimism-but- degrowth-optimism. Dengler, C., Seebacher, L.M., 2019. What about the global south? Proposal for a feminist decolonial degrowth approach. Ecol. Econ (in this issue). Deschner, C., Hurst, E., 2018. Decolonisation and Degrowth. Degrowth blog (February 1). https://www.degrowth.info/en/2018/02/decolonisation-and-degrowth/. Douthwaite, R., 1999. The Growth Illusion. Lilliput Press, Dublin. Dyer-Witheford, N., 2011. Nintendo capitalism: enclosures and insurgencies, virtual and terrestrial. Can. J. Dev. Stud. 22 (4), 965–996. Ellis, C., 2015. Solidarity for Feminist Climate Justice. Feminist Wire (April 27). http:// www.thefeministwire.com/2015/04/solidarity-for-feminist-climate-justice/. Escobar, A., 2015. Degrowth, post-development, and transitions: a preliminary con- versation. Sustain. Sci. 10 (3), 451–462. Evans, P., 2005. The new commons vs. the second enclosure movement: comments on an emerging agenda for development research. Stud. Comp. Int. Dev. 40 (2), 85–94. Federici, S., 2014. Caliban and the Witch: Women, the Body, and Primitive Accumulation. Autonomedia, Brooklyn, NY. Federici, S., 2018. Re-Enchanting the World: Feminism and the Politics of the Commons. Kairos/PM Press, Oakland, CA. First Story, 2016. Black Oak Savannah. https://www.highparknature.org/wiki/wiki.php? n=History.IndigenousHistory. Fortier, C., 2017. Unsettling the Commons: Social Movements Within, Against, and Beyond Settler Colonialism. Arbeiter Ring Publications, Winnipeg. Foster, J.B., 2011. Capitalism and degrowth: an impossibility theorem. Mon. Rev. 62, 8. https://monthlyreview.org/2011/01/01/capitalism-and-degrowth-an-impossibility- theorem/. Fotopoulos, T., 2007. Is degrowth compatible with a market economy? Int. J. Incl. Democr. 3 (1), 1–16. Fournier, V., 2013. Commoning: on the social organization of the commons. Management 16, 433–453. https://www.cairn.info/revue-management-2013-4-page-433.htm. Frost, K., 2019. First nations sovereignty, environmental justice, and degrowth in British Columbia, Canada. Ecol. Econ (in this issue). Fuente Carrasco, M.E., Barkin, D., Hernández Mecinas, E., Tapia, R.C., Mendoza Díaz, M.M., 2019. Governance from below and environmental justice: community water management from the perspective of social metabolism. Ecol. Econ (in this issue). Gaard, G., 2011. Ecofeminism revisited: rejecting essentialism and replacing species in a material feminist environmentalism. Fem. Form. 23 (2), 26–53. Gaard, G., Gruen, L., 1993. Ecofeminism: toward global justice and planetary health. Soc. Nat. 2, 1–35. Garcia, E., 2012. Degrowth and buen vivir (living well): a critical comparison. In: Presented at the 3rd International Conference on Degrowth, Venice, September 19–23, . https://www.degrowth.info/wp-content/uploads/2017/01/WS_20_FP_ GARCIA.pdf. Giacomini, T., 2016. Ecofeminism and system change: women on the frontlines of the struggle against fossil capitalism and for the solar commons. Can. Woman Stud. 31 (1–2), 95–101. Gibson-Graham, J.K., 2006. A Post-Capitalist Politics. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, MN. Gordon Nembhard, J., 2014. Collective Courage: A History of African American Cooperative Economic Thought and Practice. Pennsylvania State University Press, University Park, PA. Gorecki, J., 2014. ‘No Climate Justice Without Gender Justice’: Women at the Forefront of the People's Climate March. The Feminist Wire (September 29). http://www. thefeministwire.com/2014/09/climate-justice-without-gender-justice-women- forefront-peoples-climate-march/. Graves, F., Valpy, M., 2018a. Ford's Win Exposes the Angry Blind Spot of Canadian Democracy. The Globe and Mail (June 8). https://www.theglobeandmail.com/ opinion/article-fords-win-exposes-the-angry-blind-spot-of-canadian-democracy/. Graves, Frank, Valpy, Michael, 2018b. Canada is a tinderbox for populism. In: The 2019 Election Could Spark it. Macleans (December 3). https://www.macleans.ca/politics/ canada-is-a-tinderbox-for-populism-the-2019-election-could-spark-it/?utm_ medium=organic&utm_source=Facebook&fbclid= IwAR2eR8wEwAOQbCMcs5f8CQ51RjGSaNcJYZOQPA7D9xCE4t9NepknkI2rdeQ. Great Lakes Commons, 2013. http://greatlakescommonsmap.org/main. Green, Joyce, 2017. Making Space for Indigenous Feminism, 2nd ed. Fernwood Publishing, Halifax/Winnipeg. Gudynas, E., 2015. Buen Vivir. In: D'Alisa, G., Demaria, F., Kallis, G. (Eds.), Degrowth a Vocabulary for a New Era. Routledge, London/New York, pp. 201–204. Hess, C., 2008. Mapping the New Commons. Syracuse University Library, Syracuse, NY. https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1356835. Hess, C., Ostrom, E., 2007. Understanding Knowledge as Commons: From Theory to Practice. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. Hoeft, T., 2018. Towards the Pluriverse: How to Connect Degrowth and Ubuntu. In: Lund University Thesis HEKM51 20181, . https://lup.lub.lu.se/student-papers/search/ publication/8945696. Inter-American Commission on Human Rights, 2014. Missing and Murdered Indigenous Women in British Columbia, Canada. Organization of American States, Washington, DC. http://www.oas.org/en/iachr/reports/pdfs/indigenous-women-bc-canada-en. pdf. Kallis, G., March, H., 2014. Imaginaries of hope: the utopianism of degrowth. Ann. Assoc. Am. Geogr. 105 (2), 360–368. Kaufman, C., 2012. Getting Past Capitalism: History, Vision, Hope. Lexington Books, Lanham, MD. Kirkup, K., 2016. Carolyn Bennett Says There Are More than 1,200 Missing or Murdered Indigenous Women. Huffington Post (16 February). Klein, N., 2014. This Changes Everything: Capitalism vs. the Climate. Simon and Schuster, New York. Korten, D., 2006. The Great Turning: From Empire to Earth Community. Berrett-Koehler Publishers, Oakland, CA. Kothari, A., Demaria, F., Acosta, A., 2014. Buen Vivir, degrowth and ecological Swaraj: alternatives to sustainable development and the green economy. Development 57 (3–4), 362–375. Kuiper, E., Perkins, E., 2005. Introduction: exploring feminist ecological economics. Fem. Econ. 11 (3), 107–108. Lang, M., 2017. Degrowth: Unsuited for the Global South? Alternautas blog. http://www. alternautas.net/blog/2017/7/17/degrowth-unsuited-for-the-global-south. Latouche, S., 2003. Would the West Actually Be Happier With Less? The World Downscaled. Le Monde Diplomatique (December 12, 2003). Latouche, S., 2007. Degrowth Economics. Le Monde Diplomatique (July 3, 2007). Latouche, S., 2012. Can the left escape economism? Capital. Nat. Social. 23 (1), 74–78. Leroy, J.P., 2016. Mercado ou Bens Comuns? O papel dos povos indígenas, comunidades tradicionais e setores do campesinato diante da crise ambiental. FASE, Rio de Janeiro. http://fase.org.br/wp-content/uploads/2016/10/FASE_Mercado-ou-Bens-Comuns- JPL-PDF.pdf. Macgregor, S., 2014. Only resist: feminist ecological citizenship and the post-politics of climate change. Hypatia 29 (3), 617–633. Mann, C.C., 2005. 1491: New Revelations of the Americas Before Columbus. Alfred A. Knopf, New York. Manuel, A., Derrickson, R.M., 2015. Unsettling Canada: A National Wake-Up Call. Between the Lines, Toronto. Martinez-Alier, J., 2012. Environmental justice and economic degrowth: an alliance be- tween two movements. Capital. Nat. Social. 23 (1), 51–73. Martinez-Alier, J., Pascual, U., Vivien, F., Zaccai, E., 2010. Sustainable de-growth: mapping the context, criticisms and future prospects of an emergent paradigm. Ecol. Econ. 69, 1741–1747. Mellor, M., 1992. Breaking the Boundaries: Towards a Feminist Green Socialism. Virago Press, London. Mellor, M., 1997a. Feminism and Ecology. NYU Press, New York. Mellor, M., 1997b. Feminism and Ecology. Polity Press, Cambridge, UK. Merchant, C., 1980. The Death of Nature: Women, Ecology and the Scientific Revolution. Merchant, C., 2008. ‘The violence of impediments’: Francis Bacon and the origins of experimentation. Isis 99, 731–760. Meynen, N., 2016. Why the Degrowth Debate Is Growing. Ejolt blog (September 5). P.E.E. Perkins Ecological Economics 160 (2019) 183–190 189 http://www.thefeministwire.com/2015/05/climate-change-and-feminist-environmentalisms-closing-remarks/ http://www.thefeministwire.com/2015/05/climate-change-and-feminist-environmentalisms-closing-remarks/ http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0030 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0030 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0030 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0030 http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/25428/1/property_rights_and_economic_development.pdf http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/25428/1/property_rights_and_economic_development.pdf http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0040 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0040 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0045 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0045 http://www.csrwire.com/blog/posts/1203-the-commons-as-a-growing-global-movement http://www.csrwire.com/blog/posts/1203-the-commons-as-a-growing-global-movement http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0055 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0055 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0060 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0060 http://www.europe-solidaire.org/spip.php?article9416 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0070 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0070 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0075 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0075 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0085 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0085 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0090 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0090 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0090 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0095 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0095 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0100 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0100 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0105 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0105 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0110 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0110 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0115 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0115 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0120 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0125 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0125 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0125 https://www.socialeurope.eu/growth-pessimism-but-degrowth-optimism https://www.socialeurope.eu/growth-pessimism-but-degrowth-optimism http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0130 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0130 https://www.degrowth.info/en/2018/02/decolonisation-and-degrowth/ http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf8000 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0145 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0145 http://www.thefeministwire.com/2015/04/solidarity-for-feminist-climate-justice/ http://www.thefeministwire.com/2015/04/solidarity-for-feminist-climate-justice/ http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0155 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0155 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0160 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0160 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0165 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0165 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0170 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0170 https://www.highparknature.org/wiki/wiki.php?n=History.IndigenousHistory https://www.highparknature.org/wiki/wiki.php?n=History.IndigenousHistory http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0180 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0180 https://monthlyreview.org/2011/01/01/capitalism-and-degrowth-an-impossibility-theorem/ https://monthlyreview.org/2011/01/01/capitalism-and-degrowth-an-impossibility-theorem/ http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0190 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0190 https://www.cairn.info/revue-management-2013-4-page-433.htm http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0200 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0200 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0205 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0205 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0205 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0210 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0210 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0215 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0215 https://www.degrowth.info/wp-content/uploads/2017/01/WS_20_FP_GARCIA.pdf https://www.degrowth.info/wp-content/uploads/2017/01/WS_20_FP_GARCIA.pdf http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0230 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0230 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0230 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0235 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0235 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0240 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0240 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0240 http://www.thefeministwire.com/2014/09/climate-justice-without-gender-justice-women-forefront-peoples-climate-march/ http://www.thefeministwire.com/2014/09/climate-justice-without-gender-justice-women-forefront-peoples-climate-march/ http://www.thefeministwire.com/2014/09/climate-justice-without-gender-justice-women-forefront-peoples-climate-march/ https://www.theglobeandmail.com/opinion/article-fords-win-exposes-the-angry-blind-spot-of-canadian-democracy/ https://www.theglobeandmail.com/opinion/article-fords-win-exposes-the-angry-blind-spot-of-canadian-democracy/ https://www.macleans.ca/politics/canada-is-a-tinderbox-for-populism-the-2019-election-could-spark-it/?utm_medium=organic&utm_source=Facebook&fbclid=IwAR2eR8wEwAOQbCMcs5f8CQ51RjGSaNcJYZOQPA7D9xCE4t9NepknkI2rdeQ https://www.macleans.ca/politics/canada-is-a-tinderbox-for-populism-the-2019-election-could-spark-it/?utm_medium=organic&utm_source=Facebook&fbclid=IwAR2eR8wEwAOQbCMcs5f8CQ51RjGSaNcJYZOQPA7D9xCE4t9NepknkI2rdeQ https://www.macleans.ca/politics/canada-is-a-tinderbox-for-populism-the-2019-election-could-spark-it/?utm_medium=organic&utm_source=Facebook&fbclid=IwAR2eR8wEwAOQbCMcs5f8CQ51RjGSaNcJYZOQPA7D9xCE4t9NepknkI2rdeQ https://www.macleans.ca/politics/canada-is-a-tinderbox-for-populism-the-2019-election-could-spark-it/?utm_medium=organic&utm_source=Facebook&fbclid=IwAR2eR8wEwAOQbCMcs5f8CQ51RjGSaNcJYZOQPA7D9xCE4t9NepknkI2rdeQ http://greatlakescommonsmap.org/main http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0265 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0265 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0270 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0270 https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=1356835 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0280 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0280 https://lup.lub.lu.se/student-papers/search/publication/8945696 https://lup.lub.lu.se/student-papers/search/publication/8945696 http://www.oas.org/en/iachr/reports/pdfs/indigenous-women-bc-canada-en.pdf http://www.oas.org/en/iachr/reports/pdfs/indigenous-women-bc-canada-en.pdf http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0290 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0290 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0295 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0295 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0300 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0300 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf9000 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf9000 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0305 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0305 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0310 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0310 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0310 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0315 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0315 http://www.alternautas.net/blog/2017/7/17/degrowth-unsuited-for-the-global-south http://www.alternautas.net/blog/2017/7/17/degrowth-unsuited-for-the-global-south http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0325 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0325 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0330 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0335 http://fase.org.br/wp-content/uploads/2016/10/FASE_Mercado-ou-Bens-Comuns-JPL-PDF.pdf http://fase.org.br/wp-content/uploads/2016/10/FASE_Mercado-ou-Bens-Comuns-JPL-PDF.pdf http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0350 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0350 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0355 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0355 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0360 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0360 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0370 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0370 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0375 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0375 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0375 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0380 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0380 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0385 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf3000 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0390 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0395 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0395 http://www.ejolt.org/2016/09/degrowth-debate-growing/. Mies, M., 1986/1999. Patriarchy and Accumulation on a World Scale: Women in the International Division of Labour. Zed Books, London. Mies, M., Bennholdt-Thomsen, V., 2001. Defending, reclaiming and reinventing the commons. Can. J. Dev. Stud. 22 (4), 998–1023. Mies, M., Shiva, V. (Eds.), 2014. Ecofeminism, 2nd ed. Zed Books, London. Murota, T., Takeshita, K., 2013. Local Commons and Democratic Environmental Governance. United Nations University Press, Tokyo/New York/Paris. Narine, S., 2015. Violence against aboriginal women not an aboriginal-only issue. Windspeaker 23 (1). http://www.ammsa.com/publications/alberta-sweetgrass/ violence-against-aboriginal-women-not-aboriginal-only-issue. Nixon, L., 2015. Ecofeminist Appropriations of Indigenous Feminisms and Environmental Violence. Feminist Wire (April 30). http://www.thefeministwire.com/2015/04/eco- feminist-appropriations-of-indigenous-feminisms-and-environmental-violence/. Norrlof, Carla, 2018. Donald Trump Wants to Rewrite the Liberal Playbook that Has Kept America on Top for Decades. London School of Economics US Centre blog (February 21). Ostrom, E., 2009a. A polycentric approach for coping with climate change. In: Background Paper to the 2010 World Development Report. The World Bank, Washington DC. http://www10.iadb.org/intal/intalcdi/PE/2009/04268.pdf. Ostrom, E., 2010. Polycentric systems for coping with collective action and global en- vironmental change. Glob. Environ. Chang. 20, 550–557. Ostrom, E., 2014. A polycentric approach for coping with climate change. Ann. Econ. Financ. 15 (1), 97–134. Oxfam, 2018. Reward Work, Not Wealth. Briefing Paper (January). http://www.oxfam. org. Paulsen, S., 2017. Degrowth: culture, power and change. J. Polit. Ecol. 24 (1), 425–441. Perkins, P.E., 2017. Canadian indigenous female leadership and political agency on cli- mate change. In: Cohen, M.G. (Ed.), Climate Change and Gender in Rich Countries: Work, Public Policy and Action. Routledge, London, pp. 282–296. Pietilä, H., 1997. The triangle of the human economy: household – cultivation – industrial production. An attempt at making visible the human economy in toto. Ecol. Econ. 20, 113–127. Piketty, T., 2014. Capital in the Twenty-First Century. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA. Plumwood, V., 1993. Feminism and the Mastery of Nature. Routledge, London. Rose, C., 1986. The comedy of the commons: custom, commerce, and inherently public property. Univ. Chicago Law Rev. 53 (3), 711–772. Roser, Max, 2016. Global Economic Inequality. Our World in Data. https:// ourworldindata.org/global-economic-inequality. Roser, Max, Ortiz-Ospina, E., 2016. Income Inequality. Our World in Data. https:// ourworldindata.org/income-inequality. Rowan, C., 2019. The new rural reconstruction movement: a Chinese grass-roots move- ment for environmental sustainability and social justice. Ecol. Econ (in this issue). Salleh, A., 1997. Ecofeminism as Politics: Nature, Marx, and the Postmodern. Zed Books, London. Salleh, A. (Ed.), 2009. Eco-sufficiency and Global Justice: Women Write Political Ecology. Pluto Press, New York. Shimada, D., 2010. How can societies create common access to nature? In: The Roots and Development Process of the Bruce Trail, a Canadian Case Study. York University Faculty of Environmental Studies, Toronto (Post-doctoral research paper). http:// iasc2011.fes.org.in/papers/docs/356/submission/original/356.pdf. Shiva, V., 1988. Staying Alive: Women, Ecology, and Development. Zed Books, London. Shiva, V., Mies, M., 1993. Ecofeminism: Women, Culture, Nature. Zed Books, London. Simpson, L., 2011. Dancing on Our Turtle's Back: Stories of Nishnaabeg Re-creation, Resurgence and a New Emergence. ARP Books, Winnipeg. Spencer, P., Perkins, P.E., Erickson, J.D., 2018. Re-establishing justice as a pillar of ecological economics through feminist perspectives. Ecol. Econ. 152, 191–198. Temper, Leah, 2018a. Blocking pipelines, unsettling environmental justice: from rights of nature to responsibility to territory. Local Environ. https://doi.org/10.1080/ 13549839.2018.1536698. Temper, Leah, 2018b. Canadian clan faces gas pipelines injunction. Ecologist. https:// theecologist.org/2018/dec/06/canadian-clan-faces-oil-pipelines-injunction (6 December). Thomson, B., 2010. Pachakuti: Indigenous perspectives, edgrowth and ecosocialism. In: Climate & Capitalism, October 6. https://climateandcapitalism.com/2010/10/06/ pachakuti-indigenous-perspectives-degrowth-and-ecosocialism/. Trosper, R., 2009. Resilience, Reciprocity, and Ecological Economics: Northwest Coast Sustainability. Routledge, London/New York. Tuck, E., 2017. Can Reconciliation Take (Up) Place? ACME Lecture, Toronto. https:// www.youtube.com/playlist?list=PLRdtnJa5iycDPQ4YyfwV5YLFpo7wB_fr0. Turner, T.E., Brownhill, L.S., 2001. Gender, feminism and the civil commons: women and the anti-corporate, anti-war movement for globalization from below. Can. J. Dev. Stud. 22 (4), 805–818. Turner, N.J., Ignace, M., Ignace, R., 2000. Traditional ecological knowledge and wisdom of aboriginal peoples in British Columbia. Ecol. Appl. 10 (5), 1275–1287. Turner, T., Brownhill, L., Kaara, W., 2012. Degrowth? How about some de-alienation? Capital. Nat. Social. 23 (1), 93–104. UNDP, 2015. Imbalances in paid and unpaid work. In: United Nations Development Program, Human Development Report 2015, pp. 107–130. chapter 4. http://hdr. undp.org/sites/default/files/2015_human_development_report_0.pdf. Verma, R., 2017. Gross national happiness: meaning, measure and degrowth in a living development alternative. J. Polit. Ecol. 24 (1), 477–490. Warren, K., 2000. Ecofeminist Philosophy: A Western Perspective on What It Is and Why It Matters, Rowman & Littlefield; Lanham, MD. Whyte, K.P., 2014a. Indigenous women, climate change impacts, and collective action. Hypatia 29 (3), 599–616. Whyte, K.P., 2016. Indigenous Experience, Environmental Justice and Settler Colonialism. In: Bannon, B. (Ed.), In Nature and Experience: Phenomenology and the Environment. Rowman & Littlefield, Lanham, MD, pp. 157–174. Whyte, K.P., 2017a. Is it colonial déja vu? Indigenous peoples and climate injustice. In: Adamson, J., Davis, M. (Eds.), Humanities for the Environment: Integrating Knowledges, Forging New Constellations of Practice. Earthscan Publications, London/New York, pp. 88–104. Whyte, K.P., 2017b. Indigenous climate change studies: indigenizing futures, decolo- nizing the Anthropocene. Engl. Lang. Notes 55 (1–2), 153–162. Whyte, K.P., 2018a. Way beyond the lifeboat: an indigenous allegory of climate justice. In: Munshi, D., Bhavnani, K., Foran, J., Kurian, P. (Eds.), Climate Futures: Reimagining Global Climate Justice. University of California Press, Berkeley. Whyte, K.P., 2018b. Sovereignty, justice and indigenous peoples: an essay on settler co- lonialism and collective continuance. In: Barnhill, A., Doggett, T., Egan, A. (Eds.), Oxford Handbook of Food Ethics, pp. 345–366. Williams, C., 2005. A Commodified World? Mapping the Limits of Capitalism. Zed Books, London. Wilkinson, R., Pickett, K., 2009. The Spirit Level: Why Equality Is Better for Everyone. Penguin, London/New York, London/New York. Wily, Liz Alden, 2018. Collective land ownership in the 21st century: overview of global trends. Land 7 (68), 1–26. Women's Earth Alliance and Native Youth Sexual Health Network, 2016. Violence on the land, violence on our bodies: building an indigenous response to environmental violence. http://landbodydefense.org/uploads/files/VLVBReportToolkit2016.pdf. World Health Organization and World Bank, 2017. Tracking Universal Health Coverage: 2017 Global Monitoring Report. Wu, F., 2018. China: climate justice without a social movement? In: Munshi, D., Bhavnani, K., Foran, J., Kurian, P. (Eds.), Climate Futures: Reimagining Global Climate Justice. University of California Press, Berkeley. Xanthaki, A., 2007. Indigenous Rights and United Nations Standards: Self-determination, Culture and Land. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. P.E.E. Perkins Ecological Economics 160 (2019) 183–190 190 http://www.ejolt.org/2016/09/degrowth-debate-growing/ http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0405 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0405 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0410 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0410 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0415 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0420 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0420 http://www.ammsa.com/publications/alberta-sweetgrass/violence-against-aboriginal-women-not-aboriginal-only-issue http://www.ammsa.com/publications/alberta-sweetgrass/violence-against-aboriginal-women-not-aboriginal-only-issue http://www.thefeministwire.com/2015/04/eco-feminist-appropriations-of-indigenous-feminisms-and-environmental-violence/ http://www.thefeministwire.com/2015/04/eco-feminist-appropriations-of-indigenous-feminisms-and-environmental-violence/ http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0435 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0435 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0435 http://www10.iadb.org/intal/intalcdi/PE/2009/04268.pdf http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0455 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0455 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0460 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0460 http://www.oxfam.org http://www.oxfam.org http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0470 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0475 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0475 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0475 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0480 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0480 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0480 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0485 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0485 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0490 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0495 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0495 https://ourworldindata.org/global-economic-inequality https://ourworldindata.org/global-economic-inequality https://ourworldindata.org/income-inequality https://ourworldindata.org/income-inequality http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0510 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0510 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0515 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0515 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0520 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0520 http://iasc2011.fes.org.in/papers/docs/356/submission/original/356.pdf http://iasc2011.fes.org.in/papers/docs/356/submission/original/356.pdf http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0530 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0535 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0540 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0540 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0545 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0545 https://doi.org/10.1080/13549839.2018.1536698 https://doi.org/10.1080/13549839.2018.1536698 https://theecologist.org/2018/dec/06/canadian-clan-faces-oil-pipelines-injunction https://theecologist.org/2018/dec/06/canadian-clan-faces-oil-pipelines-injunction https://climateandcapitalism.com/2010/10/06/pachakuti-indigenous-perspectives-degrowth-and-ecosocialism/ https://climateandcapitalism.com/2010/10/06/pachakuti-indigenous-perspectives-degrowth-and-ecosocialism/ http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0565 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0565 https://www.youtube.com/playlist?list=PLRdtnJa5iycDPQ4YyfwV5YLFpo7wB_fr0 https://www.youtube.com/playlist?list=PLRdtnJa5iycDPQ4YyfwV5YLFpo7wB_fr0 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0575 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0575 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0575 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0580 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0580 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0585 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0585 http://hdr.undp.org/sites/default/files/2015_human_development_report_0.pdf http://hdr.undp.org/sites/default/files/2015_human_development_report_0.pdf http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0595 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0595 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf7000 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf7000 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0600 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0600 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf1000 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf1000 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf1000 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0610 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0610 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0610 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0610 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0615 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0615 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0620 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0620 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0620 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0625 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0625 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0625 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf4000 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf4000 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0630 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0630 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0635 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0635 http://landbodydefense.org/uploads/files/VLVBReportToolkit2016.pdf http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0650 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0650 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0655 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0655 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0655 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0660 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0921-8009(18)30302-1/rf0660 Climate justice, commons, and degrowth Introduction Ecofeminism, commons, climate justice, and degrowth Indigenous commons, climate justice, and degrowth Conclusion: equity, commons, and climate justice References work_7ei5m6rinjbz7i6f3ipra6hbsi ---- doi:10.1016/j.ijsu.2005.10.010 International Journal of Surgery (2005) 3, 233e234 www.int-journal-surgery.com EDITORIAL Distributive justice, starfish and natural disasters What does the earthquake in Kashmir have to do with the mammographic screening for early breast cancer? The link is tortuous but never the less very relevant for the readers of this journal. Last night I was giving a lecture to the PhD students at the Ludwig Institute of Cancer Research in London. In it I described the great advances that we are making in the medical treatment of breast cancer and the decreasing importance of the role of the surgeon in this disease. I then went on to expound on my thesis concerning the timing of the appear- ance of metastases in relation to the act of surgery and its link to the biological responses of the healing process.1 Indirectly this is also related to the controversy whipped up by the paper from Retsky and his colleagues published in the last issue of the Int. J. Surgery.2 They suggested that the increase in the short-term mortality from screening women under the age of 50 was related to these mechanisms [see editorials and corre- spondence in this issue]. Even if you reject that as implausable, taking the most optimistic assess- ments from the screening advocates you still have to screen about 1600 women for 10 years to save one life!3 At the end of my talk a bright young student asked me if as a result of these data whether I could see a time when surgery would no longer be a part of breast cancer management and if so how would I spend my time. After a moment’s hesita- tion I replied that yes I look forward to that day but by then I would be fully retired from clinical practice! After another moment’s hesitation I went on to say that there are many traditional areas in the surgical treatment of chronic disease when surgeons will enjoy less and less of a role yet at the same time we will always need surgeons for trauma on the roads, and for the results of natural disasters and global terrorism. 1743-9191/$ - see front matter ª 2005 Surgical Associates Ltd. Pu doi:10.1016/j.ijsu.2005.10.010 Justice This then leads me into a consideration of the ethical imperative of justice in health care. What do we mean by justice? The shorter Oxford English dictionary defines justice as: ‘‘The quality of being (morally) just or righteous’’ Lord Chief Justice Devlin provided a more useful definition e‘‘We can use the word to mean social justice and then we say that the law is just if it conforms to some social principle, such that all men are equal; that is justice in rem.’’4 Note the distinction between the law and justice. However, as far as the practice of medicine is concerned Tom Beauchamp makes it clear that our primary concern is distributive justice. ‘‘The principle of justice is really many principles about the distribution of benefits and burdens e to cite one example, an egalitarian theory of justice implies that if there is a departure from equality of distribution of health care benefit and burdens, such a departure must serve the common good and enhance the position of those who are least advantaged in society.’’5 It can therefore be judged that the principle of justice will often be in conflict with the principle of autonomy. In fact most of the toughest ethical dilemmas we face result from the quite appropri- ate tension between the ethical principles of justice and autonomy. The parable of the starfish My late brother, Professor David Baum, was a pae- diatrician of great distinction who died in office as blished by Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved. http://www.int-journal-surgery.com 234 Editorial President of the Royal College of Paediatrics and Child Health. He had a massive myocardial in- farction whilst leading a charity bike ride to raise money for the children in the camps of Kosovo. He was committed to equality of global health care for children in the name of justice. He was fond of quoting the parable of the starfish: One can sympathize with the old man when faced with the enormity of the task and also with boy whose action saves one life. As surgeons we have the dual responsibility to care for the individual and to oversee the just distribution of scarce resources in our clinics, our hospital, our health district, our nation and the under-privileged of the third world. I anticipate your cry: ‘‘We are practical men Professor how on earth are we to achieve these goals?’’ For a start whenever we are prioritizing our waiting lists we are exercising the principle of justice. We must resist the politician waiting list initiatives and insist clinical need comes before political expediency. In the inevitable wrangle over hospital resources, always remember your freedom to carry out as many varicose veins as you damn well like may mean another old lady waits another year for a hip replacement. However, taking a global perspective is even more daunting. The best way we can discharge this responsibility as surgeons is to encourage and reward our junior colleagues for taking leave of absence to work in the third world. This will increase the number of doctors in the host country and provide better experience than a 40-h week in a teaching hospital! In addition as a consultant, why not take a sabbatical and save some starfish from the sun. I know many who have done so and the reward is in the smiles of those who have lived life without hope or expectation of reaching adulthood. I passionately believe that when we consider the An old man walking the beach at dawn noticed a boy picking up a starfish and throwing it into the sea. When asked why the boy explained that the stranded starfish would die if left to lie in the morning sun. ‘‘But there are millions of starfish on the beach’’. Said the old man. ‘‘How can your efforts make a difference?’’ The boy picked up another starfish. ‘‘It makes a difference to this one,’’ he said. ethics of distributive justice, as surgeons we must accept a global perspective. Over the last two weeks the number of deaths in the Kashmiri disaster has risen to 80,000. Many of these deaths were preventable had there been adequate surgi- cal support on the ground. Yet here we are debating the value of mammographic screening for the under 50s, that ties up millions of dollars of resources and thousands of surgical man hours chasing up microscopic foci of borderline pathol- ogy with procedures that might even do harm in the short term. What kind of world do we live in when the poor of the third world die in their tens of thousands from natural disasters such as floods and earthquakes whilst the oh so precious women- folk of the richest countries of the world consume huge medical resources in chasing up phantoms? As I was watching the news bulletins about the earthquake and the Tsunami, I was moved to tears and feelings of guilt. On both occasions I stretched out my hand from the comfort of my arm chair and phoned up the number for donations that appeared on the screen at the end of the broad- casts, pledging £60.00 (90 euros, $100). I soon found out that I couldn’t buy peace of mind or salve my conscience so cheap. If you feel the same as me, please write a letter and let us know how you think the surgeons in the developed world might organize themselves to help the overworked and under resourced surgeons of the developing world. References 1. Baum M, Chaplain M, Anderson A, Douek M, Vaidya JS. Does breast cancer exist in a state of chaos? Eur J Cancer 1999; 35:886e91. 2. Retsky M, Demicheli R, Hrushesky WJM. Does surgery induce angiogenesis in breast cancer? Indirect evidence from relapse pattern and mammography paradox. Int J Surg 2005;3:179e87. 3. Rembold CM. Number needed to screen: development of a statistic for disease screening. Br Med J 1998;317: 307e12. 4. The judge, Patrick Devlin. Oxford: Oxford University Press; 1981. 5. Beauchamp TL. The four-principles approach. In: Gillon Raanan, editor. Principles of health care ethics. Chi- chester, New York, Brisbane, Toronto, Singapore: John Wiley and Sons; 1994. Michael Baum University College London, Portland Hospital, 212-214 Great Portland Street, London W1W 5QN, UK Tel.: þ44 2073908447; fax: þ44 2073908448. E-mail address: michael@mbaum.freeserve.co.uk mailto:michael@mbaum.freeserve.co.uk Distributive justice, starfish and natural disasters Justice The parable of the starfish References work_7eww7rihnbeojjwfdyc6s7626m ---- King’s Research Portal DOI: 10.1177/1474885116664191 Document Version Peer reviewed version Link to publication record in King's Research Portal Citation for published version (APA): Tebble, A. J. (2020). On the circumstances of justice. EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF POLITICAL THEORY, 19(1), 3-25. https://doi.org/10.1177/1474885116664191 Citing this paper Please note that where the full-text provided on King's Research Portal is the Author Accepted Manuscript or Post-Print version this may differ from the final Published version. If citing, it is advised that you check and use the publisher's definitive version for pagination, volume/issue, and date of publication details. And where the final published version is provided on the Research Portal, if citing you are again advised to check the publisher's website for any subsequent corrections. General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the Research Portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognize and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. •Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the Research Portal for the purpose of private study or research. •You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain •You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the Research Portal Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact librarypure@kcl.ac.uk providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 06. Apr. 2021 https://doi.org/10.1177/1474885116664191 https://kclpure.kcl.ac.uk/portal/en/publications/on-the-circumstances-of-justice(093564e6-7f4a-4c44-9508-1fa5fb03a368).html https://doi.org/10.1177/1474885116664191 1 On the Circumstances of Justice This is the final accepted version of the article published by SAGE Publishing in The European Journal of Political Theory on September 5, 2016 as doi:10.1177/1474885116664191 An epistemic account of the circumstances of justice allows one to make three important claims about the Humean and Rawlsian ‘standard account’ of those circumstances. First, and contrary to Hume, the possibility and necessity of justice are rooted not in limited beneficence or confined generosity, but in the epistemic insight that the knowledge relevant to deciding what to do with the fruits of social cooperation is for a variety of reasons uncentralisable. Second, and regardless of whether Rawlsian ethical disagreement is more persuasive as a circumstance of justice than Humean confined generosity, it does not explain the possibility and necessity of justice, for the uncentralisability of social knowledge would be decisive even under conditions of unanimity. Finally, the epistemic account not only shows what the circumstances of justice are but, contra Cohen’s critique of the standard account, also provides at least some guidance as to what justice itself may be. Adam James Tebble, Department of Political Economy, King’s College Londoni 1. Introduction The idea of the circumstances of justice, or those facts that explain both the possibility and necessity of justice, has a long pedigree in political philosophy and makes an appearance in many of the works familiar to the student of the discipline. Most notable here is an account of those circumstances often attributed to David Hume which, as Peter Vanderschraaf (2006:344, n.7) and others have commented, is almost unanimously accepted by contemporary political philosophers. To be sure, there is some debate as to whether Hume should be considered the undisputed father of the notion of the circumstances of justice. As Vanderschraaf (2006:344, n.7) has also noted, aspects of Hume’s account are foreshadowed in both Plato and Aristotle, as well as in St. Thomas Aquinas and Hobbes, 2 although unlike the Scot none of these thinkers made self-conscious reference to the idea of the circumstances of justice per se in their respective discussions. Interesting and insightful as these earlier contributions are, it will not be our objective to discuss them at length here. Rather, we will be concerned to question the persuasiveness of the modern, or standard, account of the circumstances of justice, understood as that attributed to Hume and subsequently developed by John Rawls.ii To this end I will defend a substantial revision of the standard account as part of a wider argument that questions whether Hume’s and Rawls’s respective characterisations of the circumstances of justice do the explanatory work expected of them. In the section that follows, and in acknowledging the significant differences with regard to theoretical aims and objectives that exist between them, I will set out both the account of the circumstances of justice attributed to Hume and Rawls’s development of that account, via his discussion of confined generosity and ethical disagreement as circumstances of justice in A Theory of Justice. Subsequent to this, I will lay the groundwork for my revision of the standard account by examining G. A. Cohen and Michael Sandel’s discussions of Rawls on ethical disagreement. In the case of Cohen, we will see that disagreement militates against the significance of a circumstance that both Hume and Rawls include in their accounts: moderate scarcity. Moreover, in the case of Sandel, and whilst failing to dislodge it as a circumstance of justice, we will see that there emerges a significant problem with Rawlsian disagreement that necessitates a major revision of the standard account. Building upon this, I will defend an alternative account of the circumstances of justice that emerges from a consideration of what authors working in the epistemic tradition of liberalism call society’s knowledge problem. Central here will be the claim that the standard account errs in positing either confined generosity or the propensity to disagree as explanations of the possibility and necessity of justice. Rather, it is the altogether different need to coordinate human knowledge with regard to the ends of life and the means 3 to pursue them that accounts for the possibility and necessity of justice. I will conclude my argument by considering how, if at all, our epistemic revision of the standard account may respond to some possible objections. Among these will be Cohen’s critique of the standard account as containing hidden ideological commitments. In responding to Cohen, I will claim that the circumstances of justice do not only offer guidance with respect to the conceptual question of the conditions that make justice possible and necessary, but also with respect to the question of what justice substantively requires. 2. The standard account Hume, moderate scarcity and confined generosity Traditionally understood, the circumstances of justice are those facts that explain both the possibility and necessity of justice. In the modern era what is called the standard account of those circumstances is associated with Hume and Rawls, although as we will presently see that their respective aims when discussing them are quite different It is commonly held that Hume (1751[1995]:188, 1740[1978]:486-9, 494-5) identifies two circumstances that explain the possibility, or origin, of rules of justice governing property and of (typically contractual) promise-keeping, and of how the necessity, or obligatory nature, of the artificial virtue of obeying those rules may be made intelligible to us: moderate scarcity of resources and our limited beneficence, or confined generosity.iii With respect to moderate scarcity, the possibility of rules of justice and the necessity of obeying them is established counterfactually. If we lived in a world of material abundance - let us call this world Cornucopia - there would be no need for such rules, or for a requirement for us to act justly even when our immediate interests suggest we should not, as each would have more than enough with which to make do (Hume, 1751[1995]:183-4). Hume makes this point about the relationship of moderate scarcity to justice still clearer by inviting us to assume the other extreme and imagine ourselves in a state of aggravated material scarcity. Here, and in contrast to it being unnecessary in a world of abundance, there would be no possibility of our acting justly for this virtue would be 4 ‘suspended’ and supplanted by the imperatives of ‘necessity and self-preservation’ (Hume, 1751[1995]:186). To be sure, and as both Jonathan Harrison and Cohen (2008:332, 334) point out, Hume may be understood to read the scope of justice somewhat narrowly in this respect, for his claim about abundance only shows that there would be no need for rules governing property, the keeping of promises and the virtue of our following them.iv These, however, do not exhaust all the rules that we would typically consider to be rules of justice. If, for example, under conditions of material abundance people ‘were sometimes malevolent’ society would still ‘need some rules of justice to protect each of its members from the others’, a point which we will see presently is amplified by the notion of Rawlsian disagreement (Harrison, 1981:264). Hume adopts a similar approach to establish the importance of our confined generosity, or limited beneficence as a second circumstance of justice. Were we wholly beneficent and miraculously unconfined in our generosity, he claims, we would have no need for rules of justice or for acting justly when personal interests and the limits of our affections suggest otherwise as we would always have the interests and needs of our fellows in mind. ‘[I]f everyone had the same affection and tender regard for everyone as for himself,’ Hume (1740[1978]:495) writes in the Treatise, ‘justice and injustice would be equally unknown among mankind’. Similarly, he (1740[1978]:494-5) claims that if we ‘[e]ncrease to a sufficient degree the benevolence of men ... you render justice useless, by supplying its place with much nobler virtues’. At the other extreme, and similarly to aggravated scarcity in the case of the first circumstance, were we wholly if not malevolently self-interested justice would be impossible, premised as it is upon virtuous behaviour when interests conflict, rather than upon a state of perpetual warfare like that to be found in a Hobbesian state of nature, or what Hume describes in the Enquiry (1751[1995]:187) as ‘the society of ruffians’. Rawls’s angels: from limited beneficence to ethical disagreement How, then, does Rawls fit into the standard account? As has already been noted, despite being associated with one another in the literature, there are significant differences between the approaches 5 of Hume and Rawls. First, the author of A Theory of Justice conceives of justice as something we may predicate of rules, institutions and schemes of social cooperation - or what he also calls ‘practices’(Rawls, 1999a:112. See also Rawls, 1999b:45-8; 1999c:190). Thus, in contrast to Hume, for whom we have seen justice is the artificial virtue of our following rules governing property and the keeping of promises, for Rawls justice is the virtue that makes these rules just. ‘Justice’, he (1999a:3) famously notes in A Theory of Justice, ‘is the first virtue of social institutions as truth is of systems of thought’. Moreover, and again in contrast to his predecessor, Rawls is not concerned with the circumstances of justice as either those conditions that explain the origin of rules of justice, or with how, despite its factitiousness, the virtue of following them may nonetheless be made intelligible to us. Rather he is concerned with the conditions which make it possible to characterise the rules that set the terms of social cooperation as just. We may say, then, that the Humean questions of the circumstances that explain the origin of rules of justice and which make the virtue of acting justly intelligible are different to Rawls’s question regarding the circumstances which make it possible and necessary to predicate justice of those rules. Rawls (1999a:109-10) also distinguishes himself from his Scottish predecessor by introducing a distinction between objective and subjective circumstances of justice, with the former being facts about the world and the latter facts about our ethical existence.v With respect to the first, objective, circumstance Rawls follows Hume in citing moderate material scarcity, although now as an explanation for why the terms of social cooperation can and need to be just, rather than of the origin of justice or of the virtue of our being just. ‘[A]lthough social cooperation is productive and mutually advantageous (one person’s or group’s gain need not be another’s loss)’, Rawls (1999e:256. See also Rawls, 1999d:234) notes, ‘natural resources and the state of technology are such that the fruits of joint efforts fall short of the claims that people make.’ Thus, just as in the bountiful conditions of Cornucopia there would be no need for rules of justice, so there would be no possibility of them under conditions of aggravated scarcity. ‘Natural and other resources’, he (1999a:110) writes, ‘are not so abundant that schemes of cooperation are superfluous,’ yet at the same time ‘nor are conditions so harsh that fruitful ventures must inevitably break down’.vi 6 In contrast to their agreement with regard to the first circumstance, in the case of the second, subjective, circumstance of justice, Rawls can be taken as disagreeing with Hume to the extent that it is supposed to show how it is possible and necessary to characterise the rules that set the terms of social cooperation as just. Our confined generosity, that is, does not explain the necessity of rules of justice. It is, rather, the notion of ethical disagreement that does this work. ‘[P]ersons and associations,’ Rawls claims in ‘Kantian Constructivism and Moral Theory’ (1999f:323. See also Rawls, 1999e:256, 1999d:234) ‘have contrary conceptions of the good as well as of how to realize them, and these differences set them at odds, and lead them to make conflicting claims on their institutions.’ Rawls (1999a:129) is happy, of course, to concede Hume’s point that ‘in an association of saints agreeing on a common ideal ... disputes about justice would not occur. Each would work selflessly for one end as determined by their common religion, and reference to this end ... would settle every question of right.’ The question, however, is whether such a community of ‘perfectly selfless angels’ has ever, or indeed, could ever exist, and matters are made hopelessly complicated in this regard when we pause to consider the situation of a modern pluralistic society (Vanderschraaf, 2006:3300. ‘[B]enevolence,’ Rawls (1999a:166) famously writes, ‘is at sea as long as its many loves are in opposition in the persons of its many objects.’ Similarly, he (1999a:112) comments insightfully that ‘[t]he spiritual ideals of saints and heroes can be as irreconcilably opposed as any other interests.’ Vanderschraaf (2006:330) makes this point lucidly by invoking, following C D Broad, the example of the survivors of a shipwreck. If all the survivors were such perfectly selfless angels, Vanderschraaf writes, ‘then each will be tempted to leave all of what little food they have for the others.’ Yet, doing this will result in all of them dying of hunger despite their express altruistic intentions. Because of this danger, the angelic survivors agree instead to divide the food so that each has something to eat. ‘What is necessary for justice,’ Vanderschraaf (2006:330) concludes, ‘is not moderate selfishness, but a moderate conflict of interests,’ regardless of whether the interests in question are ‘completely selfish, utterly selfless, or somewhere in between’.vii To be sure, it could be objected that, despite his own intentions, Rawls is talking past Hume and that the standard account is little more than a figment of the modern imagination. Indeed, given 7 that in seeking to explain the origin of rules of justice and the obligatory nature of just behaviour Hume is doing something altogether different to Rawls, what is called the standard account is more accurately described as Rawls’s development of his own reading of Hume, rather than of what Hume himself postulates.viii We will return to this matter in section 4, where we will see that Rawls’s are not the only grounds upon which we may reject the explanatory power of limited beneficence. For now, however, we may note on Rawls’s behalf that, were we concerned to set out the circumstances that show how the terms of social cooperation both can and need to be just, we ought not resort to Humean confined generosity to do so. Rather, the relevant subjective circumstance of justice is the fact of ethical disagreement about ends. Taken together, then, we see how the objective and subjective circumstances make justice possible and necessary insofar as it responds to the problem of the allocation of limited resources to people who, following Rawls’s development of Hume, disagree. In our imperfect world we require some way of adjudicating what should be done with the fruits of social cooperation and this is what justice achieves. 3. Ethical disagreement and the standard account Cohen, disagreement and moderate scarcity There are a diversity of responses to the standard account which, whilst certainly interesting in their own right, will not be engaged with in great detail here.ix Two responses that are relevant to our assessment of the explanatory adequacy of the standard account, however, are those of G. A. Cohen and Michael Sandel. As was suggested earlier, Cohen’s discussion of Rawlsian ethical disagreement is significant insofar as it may be read to prompt a further development of the standard account beyond that often considered to have been achieved by Rawls. Here, ethical disagreement is not just significant for the explanatory standing of Humean confined generosity, but also for the moderate material scarcity that both Hume and Rawls agree is indispensable to their respective accounts. Sandel’s discussion of Rawls’s view is also significant in this developmental respect insofar it enables us to clarify the conceptual terrain upon which an alternative epistemic account that calls into question the significance of either limited beneficence or ethical disagreement may be established. Finally, 8 Cohen’s discussion is significant in a second respect insofar as it highlights the issue of the relationship between the question of what the circumstances are in which justice is both possible and necessary and the normative question of our identifying what justice is. Leaving this discussion to the penultimate section of this paper, and discussion of Sandel’s contribution to the next section, let us commence with an analysis of Cohen’s discussion of the relationship between ethical disagreement and moderate resource scarcity. In addition to what Rawls has to say about its impact upon the standing of confined generosity, for Cohen ethical disagreement also shows why moderate resource scarcity cannot qualify as a circumstance of justice. Adopting a similar line of argument to Harrison in his discussion of Hume on moderate scarcity and malevolence, Cohen claims that Rawls’s shift from confined generosity to ethical disagreement with regard to the subjective circumstance of justice also reveals the difficulty presented by the objective circumstance of moderate scarcity to be moot. The problem here is that the example of material abundance, to which appeal is made counterfactually to establish moderate scarcity as a circumstance of justice, fails in this regard (Cohen, 2008:331, n. 88). Even under the bountiful conditions in Cornucopia, and contrary to the claim that it shows how justice would be unnecessary, there would still be conflicts of interest and hence a need for rules of justice, once it is recognised that, in addition to being capable of having what Cohen (2008:333) calls ‘spiteful motivations’, people also have different conceptions of the good that may require that we do different things with resources. This is not to say, of course, that Rawls either fails to see or ignores this point. ‘Although moderate scarcity may possibly be overcome or largely mitigated,’ he (Rawls, 1999f:326, 329) writes, ‘justice as fairness assumes that deep and pervasive differences of religious, philosophical, and ethical doctrine remain.’ The important point in this connection, however, is whether from the standpoint of a persuasive explanation of the possibility and necessity of justice, the overcoming of moderate scarcity matters. It appears that Rawls's point about mitigation is that it shows moderate scarcity to be merely a less important circumstance of justice than disagreement. But, we may concur with Cohen that it does more than this. The mitigation of 9 moderate scarcity having no impact upon ethical disagreement shows that moderate scarcity is of no explanatory import at all. Indeed, the problem of moderate scarcity’s explanatory irrelevance is deeper than Cohen recognizes. For not only may different conceptions of the good require that we do different things with resources. They may require that we refrain from doing things that other conceptions enjoin. It is plausible, for instance, that in Cornucopia one conception of the good - let us call it conception A - requires that we build place of worship x, and is indifferent to the construction of place of worship y that is required by conception B. It is also the case, however, that in Cornucopia conception B requires that only place of worship y be built, to the exclusion of x, and that another conception, conception C, is doctrinally committed to forbidding the construction of any places of worship at all. In such circumstances, it is evident that no amount of material abundance in Cornucopia would obviate the need for rules of justice to decide such conflicts peacefully. It follows, therefore, that if we would still need justice even under conditions of abundance it cannot be the case that the less demanding assumption of moderate material scarcity explains our need for it. Rawlsian disagreement, therefore, has an effect upon the standard account beyond that which both Rawls and Cohen expect. Not only is it decisive with respect to the explanatory power of confined generosity, the fact of disagreement about the ends of life is also decisive with respect to moderate material scarcity. To be sure moderate scarcity does make more vivid Rawls’s deeper, ethical explanation for the necessity of justice and of why it needs to assume its ‘peculiar’ and ‘special’ role as the first virtue of social institutions (Rawls, 1999d:234, 1999e:256). Making an explanation more vivid, however, is not the same thing as giving that explanation, and insofar as it incorporates moderate scarcity into its explanation of the possibility and necessity of justice Rawls’s development of the standard account is therefore to be rejected. Sandel, disagreement and the inverse proportionality thesis Having seen how the explanatory standing of both moderate scarcity and of confined generosity as circumstances of justice is undermined by ethical disagreement, it remains to consider whether this 10 Rawlsian reformulation of the second, subjective, circumstance of justice provides an explanation that is satisfactory. Doing so is doubly significant for we will presently see that it is out of this discussion that the need to articulate an alternative conception of the circumstances of justice becomes apparent. A useful starting point here is Sandel’s (1982:28-47, 168-72) critique of the underlying epistemic commitments of Rawls’s account and of how it undermines Rawls’s claim that justice is the first virtue of social institutions. As we have just seen, and as Sandel also tells us, it is the separateness of persons, where our diverse conceptions of the good and associated wants and desires are different that explains the possibility and necessity of justice. Yet, Sandel also wants to claim that it is not just the fact that our ends differ and that we consequently disagree either about whom we should act benevolently towards, or what doing so requires, that accounts for the need for justice. The consequences of Rawls ‘taking seriously the distinction between persons,’ Sandel (1982:171) claims, ‘are not directly moral but more decisively epistemological’ insofar as they highlight how our conceptions are largely inscrutable and opaque to others. ‘What the bounds between persons confine,’ he (1982:171) claims, ‘is less the reach of our sentiments ... than the reach of our understanding, of our cognitive access to others’. To be sure, in the case of more intimate relationships, such as those to be found within the family and amongst friends, one may have at least some knowledge of the conceptions, needs, wants and desires of others (although, as we will see presently, St. Thomas Aquinas gives us reason to be sceptical about even this much). This notwithstanding, it is what Sandel (1982:172) calls this ‘epistemic deficit’ between subjects that accounts in Rawls for the possibility, necessity and the ultimate priority or ‘pre-eminence’, of justice. ‘[W]here for Hume we need justice because we do not love each other well enough,’ he (1982:172) writes, ‘for Rawls we need justice because we cannot know each other well enough for even love to serve alone.’ Sandel, of course, is at pains to reject this view that he attributes to Rawls when claiming that considerations of fraternity and of community demonstrate that the circumstance of ethical disagreement, upon which the primacy of the virtue of justice depends, need not hold. Given, that is, a high level of fraternal feeling and benevolence of the type to be found in friendship, within the 11 family, or in community, there would be no conflict over moderately scarce resources. Moreover, ethical disagreement is only significant as a circumstance of justice if we additionally assume that we are largely inscrutable or opaque to one another. But why should we accept the Rawlsian picture of opacity, asks Sandel? A way of making Sandel’s claim clear here is to ask whether the society of angels that Rawls describes as one where there would be no need for justice could ever obtain. Clearly Rawls and other liberals think not. Yet, for Sandel, and even if the benevolence and familiarity that a society of angels could supply were not a realistic option, it may be supplied by the bonds of community. Indeed, when the constitutive bonds of community are taken into consideration, it is not at all clear that we are opaque to one another in the manner he claims Rawls believes gives justice its priority. ‘[I]n so far as our constitutive self-understandings comprehend a wider subject than the individual alone, whether a family or tribe or city or class or nation or people,’ writes Sandel (1982:172), to this extent they define a community in the constitutive sense. And what marks such a community is not merely a spirit of benevolence, or the prevalence of communitarian values, or even certain ‘shared final ends’ alone, but a common vocabulary of discourse and a background of implicit practices and understandings within which the opacity of the participants is reduced if never finally dissolved. Thus, for Sandel (1982:31) because ties of community overcome the epistemic deficit inherent in the notion of the separateness of persons, and upon which Rawls founds not just the possibility and necessity but the priority of justice, ‘justice is the first virtue of social institutions not absolutely, as truth is to theories, but only conditionally, as physical courage is to a war zone’. There is for Sandel, a relationship of ‘inverse proportionality’ (Badhwar, 1993:258) between relations of community and relations of justice, where the extent to which the former are extant is the extent to which the latter are surplus to requirements. We need not be detained by the question of whether Sandel’s reading of Rawls on the separateness of persons is a persuasive one. More important for the purposes of assessing Rawls’s 12 claim about disagreement is an assessment of whether Sandel’s claim about inverse proportionality is true. Answering this depends upon which of the two senses in which the inverse proportionality thesis may hold one considers. The ethical version of the inverse proportionality thesis holds that ‘[i]n so far as mutual benevolence and enlarged affections could be cultivated more widely, the need for ‘the cautious, jealous virtue of justice’ would diminish in proportion, and mankind would be better for it’ (Sandel, 1982:169). By contrast, the epistemic version of the inverse proportionality thesis, the one that denies what Sandel (1982:172) calls the ‘epistemic deficit’, holds that ‘[i]n so far as justice depends for its pre-eminence on the separateness or boundedness or persons in the cognitive sense, its priority would diminish as that opacity faded and this community deepened’. As we have already seen, one reason to doubt the truth of the ethical reading of the inverse proportionality thesis is that benevolent people may still disagree about intermediate ends even if they do agree about ultimate ends. Rawls, for example, claims in establishing the explanatory importance of disagreement, that even benevolently or altruistically-motivated individuals may disagree about what to do with resources, a point which Simon Caney (1991:512, n.8) notes is also to be found in Kant. Similarly, for Aquinas even in an association of saints there may still be disagreement about what action is required and in this connection we may recall Rawls’s rejection of confined generosity. Of course, for Sandel friendship or community in its highest form obviates the need for justice because it involves the pursuit of goals known and shared by all. Yet, for Aquinas even under such circumstances, and even if this were an appropriate way to understand either friendship or community, justice would nevertheless be required. As Schwartz Porzecanski (2004:39. See also Schwartz Porzecanski, (2007:124-7) highlights in his reading of Aquinas, ‘[s]ince two or more courses of action may legitimately be seen as instantiating the common goal, reference to the common goal alone is not sufficient in solving disputes.’ Aquinas’s point is echoed by Badhwar (1993:9). Even if we assume shared final ends they would not aid us in making decisions about the intermediate ends that are subordinate to them. Thus, writing with respect to the example of a family who agree on final ends, but who at the same time have to make decisions about how they will be pursued she (Badhwar, 1993:10) concludes that ‘[r]eference to a common good will not ... settle every question of 13 right’. Similarly, Caney (1991:512) contends that the claim about benevolence presupposes that ‘there will only be need for reference to a set of rights if people are selfish.’ Yet, citing the examples of a highly benevolent religious community where there is dispute over the position of women with respect to office-holding, and the problem of altruists’ dilemmas, even under conditions of benevolence, individuals still need rights because they may ‘still disagree about who should have what’ (Caney, 1991:512).x Thus, contrary to Sandel’s claim about community, even if there is a goal that everyone knows and shares, it does not follow that there is no need to accommodate conflicting interests and aims. There is a more profound reason for rejecting Sandel’s inverse proportionality thesis in its ethical guise and thus side with Rawls on disagreement. Even if Sandel were right that relationships of benevolence obviate the need to demand that our rights be respected or that justice be meted, it does not follow for at least two reasons that we should not have such rights, especially when the reasons why people act benevolently may be morally troubling. Citing the contrasting examples of an altruistic office worker who performs all the undesirable tasks in full knowledge that he has as equal a right to more pleasurable duties as his colleagues, and of the housewife who alone does all the chores but who never questions whether this is fair or just, ‘[u]nanimity and benevolence,’ Caney (1991:512) writes, ‘are often generated in non-autonomous ways’. Susan Moller Okin makes a similar point in critiquing Sandel’s Humean claim that because love can do the work of justice within domestic settings, the family is not marked by the circumstances of justice. Citing the practice of couverture, she shows that even if relationships of love provide guidance for resolving many if not most conflicts of interest within such settings, it does not follow that they ought to resolve them all and that there is therefore no need for relationships of justice in them. ‘[E]ven if wives never had occasion to ask for their just share of the family property, due to the generosity and spontaneous affection of their husbands,’ she (1989:30-1) writes, ‘we would be unable to assess the families in which they lived from a moral point of view unless we knew whether, if they did ask for it, they would be considered entitled to it.’ 14 For Caney, such examples are instructive insofar as they make clear what Rawls has to say about disagreement and the priority of justice, and why Sandel’s discussion of community ties and the inverse proportionality thesis fails to grasp it. Rawls’s claim about the priority of justice does not commit one to the view that it must be invoked on all occasions, but rather that it needs to be available when we do need to call upon it. Even if relationships among families, friends and communities are usually benevolent, that is, it does not follow that justice is unnecessary. Thus, for Caney Sandel confuses the issue of whether we may on occasion waive our rights with that of whether we require them. Individuals, that is, may waive their rights when benevolence reigns, but that is not the same as their not requiring them, or that their background institutions need not be just. Personal relations need not always be marked by justice - indeed, it would be odd and oppressively dull if they were - but our institutions, such as a regime of rights and liberties upon which we may make claims upon one another about the fruits of social cooperation, including in usually benevolent intimate personal settings, do need to be marked by them. 4. The circumstances of justice: an epistemic view From the terms of social cooperation to the terms of social coordination Given our agreement with Rawls on the implications of ethical disagreement for confined generosity, and with Cohen on its implications for moderate scarcity, and granted that the ethical variant of Sandel’s inverse proportionality thesis fails to dislodge it, it looks as if ethical disagreement, and with it at least part of the standard account, remains unvanquished. Having vindicated Rawls’s position with regard to the ethical inverse proportionality thesis, therefore, we turn now to the question of the persuasiveness of Sandel’s argument in its epistemic guise. Doing so is important not just because it enables us to assess Sandel’s critique of Rawls on disagreement further but because, crucially for present purposes, it brings to light a problem that leads us to ultimately part company with Rawls and build an alternative, epistemic, conception of the circumstances of justice. 15 We may assess the epistemic variant of the inverse proportionality thesis in two distinct ways, the first of which is to assess the degree to which it holds true in the case of close, or what we may call face-to-face, social ties. One reason to reject Sandel’s argument as grounds for his claim that close social ties may do the work that Rawls claims justice ought is because even in the case of relationships within families and between friends the problem of interpersonal inscrutability or opaqueness, and of the epistemic deficit that is attendant to it, still remains. As was hinted at in our discussion of the ethical variant of the inverse proportionality thesis, Aquinas claims that justice is still needed between friends, for even friends do not have direct knowledge of one another’s motives or desires. ‘There is no unmediated access to the heart, not only because what occurs in the heart is hidden by the body - the imperfect vehicle of expression of the heart - but also because of the fact that “the will shuts up its secrets” [voluntas claudens sua secreta]’ (Schwartz Porzecanski, 2007:126). To assume that friendship is solvent of the epistemic opacity upon which the need for justice is founded would be to assume too much. As Aquinas (2014:I.qu.57a.4c) puts it in the Summa, ‘all that is in the will, and all things that depend only on the will, are known by God alone’. Moreover, and to the extent that mutual inscrutability may not be overcome by close social ties, Sandel is wrong to extend his argument to the case of inscrutability within communities where these too are solely marked by race-to-face relations. If we assume, reasonably, that a face-to-face community is no more and no less than a complex of face-to-face relationships, then Aquinas’s problem would also hold. It is at this juncture where we not only encounter a second set of reasons to reject Sandel’s epistemic variant of the inverse proportionality thesis, his critique of disagreement and with it the priority of justice. Most significantly, in assessing Sandel’s epistemic argument we may also uncover a different but more telling set of reasons to reject the significance of both Humean confined generosity and Rawlsian disagreement themselves as circumstances of justice. First, even if we had reason to doubt Aquinas’s view of the moral epistemology of relationships in face-to-face communities and agree with Sandel that there is no epistemic deficit in them, Sandel is nevertheless wrong to claim that the epistemic deficit does not exist in all forms of community and that justice is therefore ill-suited as a model for social cooperation. That is, even if we were to part with Aquinas 16 and accept Sandel’s claim that there is no epistemic deficit in face-to-face communal settings, he is wrong in the case of modern complex societies. Caney’s (1991:512) objection that ‘[m]odern societies are not analogous to such close-knit groups and thus the circumstances of justice do obtain’ becomes salient here, for it is not only the basis upon which he makes a claim about Sandel’s political naïveté; that it is unrealistic of Sandel to think that societies are not marked by conflict. Caney (1991:512) also claims that the examples of benevolent, conflict-free relationships Sandel cites are importantly limited with respect to modern societies insofar they are conspicuous by their absence relative to the sum total of all relationships to be found within them. To be sure, Caney’s point here is a different one to Aquinas’s with respect to the inscrutability or opaqueness of the soul. The problem is not that the innermost thoughts and motivations of even those closest to us are unknowable or knowable only to God, although the personal disappointments and betrayals that punctuate our lives may attest to this being the case. Rather, it is the inscrutability that accompanies social distancing in complex, or what Hume (1740[1978]:487) calls ‘large’ societies, that is decisive in this respect. Sandel’s friendship/family model is for Carey unpersuasive and cannot serve as an alternative form of social bonding and mutual knowing that exposes the contingency rather than the priority of justice not just because it naïvely assumes away the problem of conflict. It fails to fulfil this role because it is blind to the fact that, in the overwhelming majority of circumstances, we do not and cannot know either what our fellows want, need or require, the relative intensity with which they do so, nor which bundles of resources and production processes are most appropriate for meeting them. Given that the intimate face-to-face nature of the relationships to be found among friends, within the family and within community cannot therefore serve as a model of relations in large or complex societies, it would be ‘implausible,’ and not just naïve Caney (1991:512) suggests, ‘to think that political society could be conceived along these lines’. The persuasiveness of Caney’s response to Sandel notwithstanding, defenders of ethical disagreement should not take too much comfort from his argument. The point he makes about the epistemology of social scale is not only noteworthy because of what it rejects in Sandel’s discussion. It gains an additional significance in drawing our attention to an altogether different problem, 17 overlooked in the epistemic musings of Sandel, that undermines the explanatory power of ethical disagreement as a circumstance of justice and with it the persuasiveness of the standard account as developed by Rawls. In contrast to the standard account, what we may call the epistemic approach to the circumstances of justice that Caney’s observation anticipates is not concerned with the implications our ethical lives may have for how the subjective circumstance should be understood. It is concerned, rather, with the implications of the subjectivity of human knowledge and of social complexity. A useful starting point to build upon Caney’s observation and construct an alternative account of the circumstances of justice is the thought of one of the best known defenders of the epistemic variety of liberalism, Friedrich Hayek. Of course, despite being familiar with the work of both Hume and Rawls, Hayek never wrote about the circumstances of justice. Indeed, whilst certainly familiar with Hume’s discussion, he never used the term in his written work (Hayek, 1976a: 112–113, 1967b: 350). Nevertheless, Hayek’s approach gains entry into our discussion via his core insight that the knowledge of the circumstances relevant to the direction of cooperative efforts, including the division of its fruits - that is, the knowledge of the diversity of human needs and wants, their relative value and the most appropriate means of satisfying them - is never given in its entirety to any single individual. The first reason Hayek gives for this is because it is knowledge that is subjectively held by different people acting under different circumstances. We can imagine a state of affairs, for instance where Paul believes, as he has always done, that desired good x is best made with resource p, whilst his friend Peter has recently discovered that resource q is far better for this purpose. In contrast to both of them, however, Peter’s neighbours Penny and Patricia believe that resources shouldn’t be used for making something as devoid of value as x, but should be employed instead to satisfy the far more pressing need for good y. Precisely, then, because deciding what is of value and of how what is of value should be produced is dependent upon the beliefs of different individuals, for Hayek the question of how cooperative efforts are to be directed cannot be assumed to be resolvable upon the basis of objectively-given knowledge. 18 Hayek’s claim about the subjectivity of knowledge gains its full significance, however, when we recall the distinction between face-to-face and complex social relations from our discussion of Sandel. Under face-to-face conditions the subjectivity of knowledge presents no real problem for successful social cooperation, for each either already knows, or can without great cost come to know, the needs and wants of all the rest, how best to satisfy them and of how to act accordingly (Tebble, 2016: 28–29). For epistemic liberals, however, matters are quite different when we participate in cooperative schemes that extend beyond the ken of face-to-face social formations. In such complex societies the knowledge relevant to successful social cooperation is not only the subjectively held knowledge of different individuals, but the subjectively held knowledge of different individuals who, in the overwhelming majority of cases, are not in direct contact with one another, with the consequence that it is never given in the way that would make social cooperation as relatively costless as it is in face-to-face settings. To be sure, there is a sense in which this knowledge can be said to be given, as it is after all contained within society when viewed as a single collectivity. The important point, however, is that its dispersal among what we may call mutually ignorant individuals means that each has access to a different part of the sum, and therefore does not know what all the rest know, even though this would be relevant to ensuring that cooperative efforts are directed successfully (Tebble, 2016: 30–32). It is not only spatial distancing that accounts for the cognitive separateness and epistemic deficit prevalent in modern societies or, what theorists working in the epistemic tradition of liberalism call society’s knowledge problem. The question is not just that of who is in possession of the knowledge relevant to successful social cooperation, or of the distance between them, but also of the kind of knowledge this knowledge is that is decisive. Thus, related to its dispersal, and again showing why it defies centralization, are the facts that as subjective knowledge this knowledge is often circumstantial and fleeting. Unlike our scientific knowledge, for example, this knowledge is knowledge of specific circumstances that may only be of temporary duration, but which are nonetheless relevant to our decisions. Fourth, and perhaps most significantly for Hayek (1948a, 1948b, the subjectively-held knowledge of mutually-ignorant individuals is also often tacit in nature, 19 embodied in different traditions and practices whose action-guiding significance to the decisions of others is only ever communicated when acted upon by those who possess it. That is, it is knowledge that its possessors do not realize that they have, let alone that somebody else may know they have and could therefore make use of independently of them. Finally, recent work in the epistemic liberal tradition has shown how the knowledge problem is also significant because the circumstances to which agents must respond if their plans are to be successful are a continually changing result of their own past decisions and those of their fellows. In this connection we may note the contribution of complex adaptive systems theory and conceive the economy of a modern society as a complex adaptive system (Tebble, 2016:31-33). Of particular significance in this respect are two features that complex adaptive systems manifest. First, and as the above suggests, in contrast to complex physical systems that also display hallmark features of complexity such as self-organisation or, following Hayek, spontaneous order, complex adaptive systems are affected by the intentional agency of the elements that feature in them.xi Moreover, and related to this, complex adaptive systems are characterised by the phenomenon called parallel processing where individual agents respond to their circumstances simultaneously, although unbeknownst to one another. The result of these behaviours is that the overall economic context to which agents respond and with regard to which they must make decisions, in turn becomes the future context which they have helped to shape precisely as a result of their prior adaptive responses. In the complex economic adaptive order of a large-scale society, therefore, and regardless of whether one’s primary interests are one’s own or those of others, the circumstances that each must take into account in order to satisfy them are in a constant state of effervescent change brought about by the mutually affecting simultaneous adaptive responses of each to the activities of all the rest. It is not the case, therefore, that the knowledge problem is a one-off coordination problem that, at some point and with the requisite will and effort, may be solved. Rather, precisely because mutually ignorant agents simultaneously impact upon one another’s circumstances, and with this the chances of their respective plans being successful, the knowledge problem and associated need for mutual coordination are not 20 only ever-present with respect to a continually changing environment, but indeed intensify as the cooperative space expands to include more and more mutually impacting agents. The knowledge problem as a circumstance of justice These insights amount to an epistemic liberal variant of Sandel’s notion of the cognitive separateness of persons. Agents engaged in social cooperation are opaque to one another not only for the reasons that Sandel suggests are implicit in Rawls’s account, but because of the insuperable spatio-temporal distancing that exists between them. Thus, in addition to the inscrutability of the human soul, cognitive separateness and its attendant epistemic deficit arise from social complexity and it is in this sense that we are physically, and not only spiritually or ethically, distant from one another. Moreover, and again in contrast to the concerns of Sandel, it is the epistemic deficit manifested in society’s knowledge problem that assumes central importance with regard to the circumstances of justice. Similarly to the counterfactual reasoning that we have seen Hume and Rawls engage in with respect to the establishment of moderate scarcity, confined generosity and ethical disagreement, we may adopt a similar approach to establish the significance of the knowledge problem. In circumstances of what we may call aggravated solipsism - where each only ever has knowledge of their own needs and where knowledge of the preferences of others and the means to satisfy them is permanently absent - knowledge coordinating rules of justice would be impossible because coordination itself would be impossible. Similarly, were we to find ourselves bestowed with the power of omniscience, the rules of justice that enable the selfish, the moderately selfish and the wholly beneficent to coordinate their activities would, like coordination itself, be unnecessary. ‘[I]n a society of omniscient persons,’ Hayek (1982:II.39) claims, ‘there would be no room for a conception of justice: every action would have to be judged as a means to bringing about known effects, and omniscience would presumably include knowledge of the relative importance of the different effects.’ Most significantly, it is in this connection that we may claim that the knowledge problem deals a fatal blow to the explanatory potency of the two principal contributions to the standard account. Of course, in making such a claim it is important not to misrepresent Hume, for we have 21 seen that it is open to question whether he conceives of the purpose of his contribution in the way that Rawls and subsequent writers on the standard account think. It may well be the case, therefore, that we ought not resort to the notion of confined generosity to explain how the terms of social cooperation both can and need to be just, but this is not something that Hume is concerned to do in the first place. Yet, even if we accept that his purposes are quite different to Rawls’s, and in so doing go so far as to eschew all notion of there being a unified standard account, there is still an important epistemic case to be made against Hume’s view on its own terms. The origin of rules of justice requiring respect for property rights and the keeping of promises, that is, is not explained by the steady growth of small-scale societies gradually undermining the natural bonds of sympathy that would otherwise obviate the need for them, as Hume seeks to show in the Treatise (Clayton Hubin, 1979:4-5). Rather, our revision of the circumstances of justice explains the origin of such rules on the epistemic grounds that, without them, the gradual expansion of the terms of social cooperation would render the communication to each of the consequences of the actions of all the rest - so that evermore disparate plans may be realised in conformity with otherwise unknowable underlying conditions - increasingly fraught. Similarly, with respect to the virtue of our obeying rules of justice, even if there were complete altruism rather than confined generosity the knowledge problem would nevertheless necessitate just behaviour so that uncentralisable but nonetheless relevant knowledge of ever- changing resource needs and availabilities could be coordinated under complex conditions. It is not, therefore, as Hume seeks to show in the Enquiry, that without an account of moderate scarcity and confined generosity it would not be possible to explain why, despite being artificial, the virtue justice is nonetheless obligatory (Clayton Hubin, 1979:5). Rather, and regardless of whether we imagine ourselves to be wholly or partially beneficent, in Humean large societies that extend beyond the ken of the face-to-face group - where each knows of the needs of all the rest and of the appropriate means to satisfy them - we are obliged to act justly because we are never in a position to know all that we would need to know in order to attend adequately not only to our own needs, but to those of our overwhelmingly unseen fellows. Thus, as Harrison (1981:266) makes clear, even in a society where 22 everybody had ‘tenderness for every man’ there would still be a need for rules of justice (including rules governing exchange) and the need to clearly delineate proprietary boundaries to prevent ‘disorganisation’. ‘It follows,’ he (1981:266) concludes, ‘that Hume is mistaken when he remarks that if benevolence were strong enough to be a motive to obey rules of justice, such rules would be unnecessary.’ Indeed, as Hayek (1982:II.83) claims in his discussion of justice, under complex circumstances there is still ‘no possibility for the individual to know what he would have to do to secure a just remuneration of his fellows’, even if he were morally motivated to do so. In addition to the doubt cast upon Hume’s explanation, our epistemic revision of the standard account shows the weaknesses of Rawls’s account with regard to the justice of schemes of social cooperation. Even if there were Rawlsian unanimity about ends, the knowledge problem would nevertheless reveal the necessity of just schemes of social cooperation. ‘All the possible differences in men's moral attitudes amount to little,’ Hayek (1948c:14) writes, so far as their significance for social organization is concerned, compared with the fact that all man's mind can effectively comprehend are the facts of the narrow circle of which he is the center; that, whether he is completely selfish or the most perfect altruist, the human needs for which he can effectively care are an almost negligible fraction of the needs of all members of society. Even if we were to agree upon ends, therefore, we would still be faced with the problem of not knowing all that we would need to know in order to ensure that the decisions of each dovetailed with those of all the rest so as to make their realisation likely. Even if it obviates the need to include moderate scarcity and confined generosity in the standard account, then, ethical disagreement is not as decisive a circumstance of justice as the knowledge problem. It is not only, therefore, that were everybody to have ‘tenderness for every man’ there would still be a need for rules of justice so as to prevent disorganisation (Harrison, 1981:266). ‘[T]he possibility of justice,’ Hayek (1982:I.13) concludes, ‘rests on [the] necessary limitation of our factual knowledge, and that insight into the 23 nature of justice is therefore denied to all those constructivists who habitually argue on the assumption of omniscience.’ It is, then, the objective fact of our permanently limited knowledge - whereby each of us is only ever in possession of but a tiny fraction of all the knowledge necessary for rational economic decisions to be made - rather than the (moderate) scarcity of resources, our reluctance to agree, or the truncated nature of our affections that explains our need for justice. To be sure, the point at issue in this regard is not to be found in any divergence with either Hume or Rawls’s respective characterisations of the hearts of men. Rather, it is the fact that, unlike either limited beneficence or disagreement, the circumstance that explains the possibility and necessity of justice is objective. Regardless of whether we imagine ourselves to be wholly or only partially beneficent, or in agreement about ends or not, the facts of the subjectivity of knowledge and of social complexity mean that, in either case, we would still not be in any position to know all that we would need to know in order to attend to the needs of our overwhelmingly unseen fellows in complex societies. Rather than drawing philosophical attention to the need for setting the just terms of social cooperation, therefore, the knowledge problem highlights the need for setting the just terms of social coordination. 5. Objections Rawls, knowledge and reasonable disagreement There are at least two objections that those keen to defend Rawls may raise at this point. The first is that, regardless of what it may tell us about the standing of disagreement, the epistemic account tells us nothing new. After all Rawls (1999a:110) does mention that, along with other shortcomings of ‘knowledge, thought and judgment’ the subjective circumstances of justice are characterised by the ‘incompleteness’ of our knowledge. Yet, given that we have argued that the knowledge problem with which epistemic liberals are concerned is an objective rather than subjective circumstance, it seems that the likelihood of Rawls meaning this in the same sense epistemic liberals do is remote to say the least. Moreover, and regardless of whether it is the same as the problem identified by epistemic liberals, it is also clear that for Rawls the incompleteness of knowledge is relevant only insofar as it 24 helps to explain what is for him the more important point of our ethical disagreement. ‘Some of these defects,’ he (1999a:110) writes, ‘spring from moral faults, from selfishness and negligence; but to a large degree, they are simply a part of man’s natural situation’. We do not need to deny the veracity of this claim about our natural situation, however, in order to sustain the argument about the knowledge problem as the primary circumstance of justice. If our claim about the knowledge relevant to successful social cooperation is of greater significance than the truncated nature of human affection or our propensity to disagree about the ends of life is true then the question of whether the incompleteness of knowledge is also rooted in humanity’s fallen moral standing is moot. Another important objection to the argument set out here is that it rests upon a mischaracterization of Rawls’s position. Particularly when discussing public reason and the burdens of judgment in later work, Rawls (1993[2005]:54-8, 66, 217, (2001[2003]:35-6, 83) is after all concerned to emphasize not disagreement but reasonable disagreement about justice. Here, and regardless of how impartial or altruistic people may be, they will continue to disagree in their religious, philosophical and moral judgments. Disagreements in these matters are therefore inevitable even among rational and reasonable people and this is known by the parties in the Original Position. It is because of this, moreover, that we are expected to forsake appeals to religious and other claims over which reasonable persons can be assumed to disagree when considering the requirements of justice, and instead appeal only to ideas that are held to be part of a liberal democratic political culture and as such may be assumed to be acceptable to all as both reasonable and rational (Rawls, 1993[2005]:217. Rawls’s notion of reasonable disagreement has of course attracted much critical attention in the literature and space will not permit us to enter into its merits here.xii What is significant for the assessment of the persuasiveness of our argument, however, is the place that reasonable disagreement occupies on the spectrum of possible positions that one may adopt regarding the subjective circumstance of justice. We will recall that the discussion thus far has been conducted within the context of an assessment of how differing degrees of disagreement impact upon the possibility and necessity of justice. Here we have claimed, with Rawls, that intractable disagreement renders justice impossible but that, as we have just seen and following Cohen, unanimity fails to make 25 justice unnecessary. Importantly, however, accepting this also shows why reasonable disagreement does not undermine the force of the epistemic argument. Precisely, because reasonable disagreement occupies a position somewhere between disagreement and unanimity - it is a stronger assumption than mere disagreement, but a weaker one than unanimity - it provides no reason to withdraw the claim about the significance of the knowledge problem for the second circumstance of justice. If it is accepted that reasonable agreement is merely a qualified form of ethical unanimity, and that unanimity does not undermine our claim about the knowledge problem, then reasonable disagreement is no more a circumstance of justice than its stronger, unqualified, relative. Cohen, ideology and the nature of justice In contrast to those above that defenders of Rawls may seek to raise, Cohen’s discussion leads to an altogether different and broader objection to the standard account of which the epistemic revision defended here is one version. Here the focus is not upon the alleged failure of the circumstances of justice to adequately ground justice but, as was mentioned in passing in section 3, upon the question of what justice is. That is, for Cohen the question of the circumstances that make justice both possible and necessary is entirely different to the question of what justice is. It is the elision of these two questions in discussion of the circumstances of justice, however, that in his view reveals the standard account to be ideologically loaded, insofar as it serves to obscure liberalism’s unadmitted individualist and capitalist commitments (Cohen, 2008:331). Hume’s discussion, Cohen explains, assumes a pre- given substantive account of justice itself as the artificial virtue of observing rules of property and of promising. But this is to put the matter back to front, for all that the circumstances tell us is that this kind of justice is either impossible or unnecessary under conditions of aggravated scarcity and extreme selfishness or material abundance and extreme beneficence respectively. Cohen makes his point via an analogy with the notion of craftsmanship. In order to know in which circumstances craftsmanship would be possible, he explains, we would first need to know what constituted craftsmanship. Cohen’s answer to this is that craftsmanship would be possible under conditions of limited abundance and limited talent. ‘But all of that’, he (2008:332) tells us, ‘follows from what 26 craftsmanship is and has no bearing on what it is.’ On this reading, therefore, the standard account of the circumstances of justice is more honestly described as the liberal account.xiii Beyond what it may tell us about t Hume’s account, much of the persuasiveness of Cohen’s argument depends upon how strongly we interpret the first part of his phrase ‘no bearing’. That the circumstances of justice have no bearing whatsoever upon the question of justice is an overstatement and, regardless of the unadmitted ethical commitments of Hume and Rawls, the epistemic view can give us some guidance as to why this is so. Firstly, the fact that no individual is in a position to authoritatively claim what an optimal outcome for society ought to be nor, even if this were known, what its achievement would practically require, suggests that justice must be concerned with offering an account of how the knowledge relevant to deciding these questions may be communicated across society. That is, justice must secure not a predetermined division of the fruits of social cooperation, but rather a procedure for the ongoing determination, under irrevocable conditions of moderate scarcity and the knowledge problem, of what that division should be. Against this view Cohen could claim that, similarly to the problem of defining what justice is in advance, the epistemic approach also fails because it too relies upon a controversial ethical assumption from the outset. That is, it is only because epistemic liberals already believe that private interests ought to be pursued that the knowledge problem, and the need to coordinate in spite of it, can be posited as significant. Such a response, however, is inadequate. As our discussion of face-to-face and complex coordination in the previous section suggested, even the successful pursuit of collective rather than private interests in a complex society would be confronted with the knowledge problem, because it would still be unclear what each would need to do, from within the confines of circumstances known only to them, to coordinate activities so that those interests could be satisfied (Tebble, 2016:28-33). The significance of the knowledge problem as a circumstance of justice and the consequent need for a procedural account of justice therefore, are not premised upon an unadmitted, undefended ethical individualism. They are premised upon the knowledge coordination problem presented by the subjectivity of knowledge and of social scale. Importantly, and to press the counter-objection still further, if this much is granted the epistemic account offers even more than the minimal guidance 27 above, for it not only suggests an account of procedural justice, but of pure procedural justice in the sense specified by Rawls. Here, and unlike a perfect conception such as the equal division of a cake guaranteed by the awarding of the allocational task to a person who may eat only the last portion, or an imperfect conception (such as a trial that seeks to discover criminal culpability), there is no external criterion for what constitutes a just outcome, other than conformity with the procedure itself (Rawls, 1999a:73-78). Moreover, we may also be more specific than Cohen suggests with regard, if not to the question of whether the circumstances of justice aid us in identifying what procedures are appropriate, then at least with regard to which are not. Minimally, and if the epistemic circumstances of justice are taken seriously, tyranny and oligarchy do not look promising as procedures for making just decisions about the fruits of social cooperation on account of their assuming that the all knowledge relevant to doing so is accessible to either one or a few. In fact, however, our revision of the standard account is able to provide more than negative guidance, for there is good reason to believe that democratic theory may provide a plausible candidate theory of pure procedural justice in addition to the market proceduralism that epistemic liberals may favour.xiv 6. Conclusion An epistemic reading of the circumstances of justice makes clear the shortcomings of the standard account. First, with respect to Hume’s contribution, the epistemic reading has shown that it is not our limited beneficence that, along with moderate scarcity, explains either the origin of rules of justice or the virtue of obeying them. Indeed, to the extent that it suggests we disagree with Hume in this regard, the epistemic reading of the circumstances of justice concurs with Rawls that it is ethical disagreement that does more powerful explanatory work in this respect. Importantly, however, we have concurred with Cohen that the more important place that Rawslian disagreement occupies in the explanatory order also obviates the need to include moderate scarcity, as both Hume and Rawls do. Most significantly, however, and beyond any claims we may wish to make about the standing of moderate scarcity and confined generosity as circumstances of justice, our epistemic reading also shows that, contra Rawls, the fact of our propensity to disagree about the ends of life, reasonably or 28 otherwise, does not explain why justice is both possible and necessary. Rather, it is the knowledge problem resultant form the fact of the subjectivity of human knowledge and of modern complex conditions found in what Hume calls large societies that explains this need. Even if we were entirely altruistic and in unanimous agreement about what to with the fruits of social cooperation, we would still need rules of justice to offer us a means of making adequate decisions in this respect. Finally, it has been claimed that the epistemic revision of the standard account not only tells us why justice is both possible and necessary. Contra Cohen, it offers at least some guidance as to what justice is, to the extent that different candidate conceptions make the coordination of otherwise inaccessible knowledge in large societies possible. There are, of course, many such conceptions that could qualify as plausible theories of justice in this regard. Which is most suitable, and whether the epistemic circumstances of justice may tell us why, however, are questions which we must leave for another occasion. 29 Bibliography Aquinas (2014) Summa Theologiae. Oxford: Oxford University Press Badhwar NK (1993) The Circumstances of Justice: Pluralism, Community, and Friendship. Journal of Political Philosophy 1(3): 250-276 Broad CD (1930) Five Types of Ethical Theory. Oxford: Clarendon Press Caney S (1991) Sandel’s Critique of the Primacy of Justice: A Liberal Rejoinder. British Journal of Political Science 21(4): 511-521 Clayton Hubin D (1979) The Scope of Justice. Philosophy and Public Affairs 9: 3-24 Cohen GA (2008) Rescuing justice and equality. Harvard, Ma.: Harvard University Press Harrison J (1981) Hume’s Theory of Justice. Oxford: Clarendon Press Hart HLA (1994) The Concept of Law (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press Hayek FA (1948a) Economics and Knowledge. In: Hayek FA Individualism and Economic Order, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 33-56 Hayek FA(1948b) The Use of Knowledge in Society. In: Hayek FA Individualism and Economic Order, pp. 77-91 Hayek FA (1948c) Individualism: true and false. In: Hayek, F. A., Individualism and Economic Order, pp. 1-32 Hayek FA (1960) The Constitution of Liberty. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul Hayek FA (1967a) The Legal and Political Philosophy of David Hume. In: Hayek, F. A. Studies in Philosophy, Politics and Economics. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, pp. 106-121 Hayek FA (1967b) Freedom and coercion: some comments on a critique by Mr. Ronald Hamowy. In: Hayek FA Studies in Philosophy, Politics and Economics. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, pp. pp. 348-350 Hayek FA (1982) Law, Legislation and Liberty. 3 vols. London: Routledge Hope S (2010) ‘The Circumstances of Justice’. Hume Studies 36(2): 125-148 Hume D (1740[1978]) A Treatise of Human Nature. Oxford; Oxford University Press 30 Hume D (1751[1995]) An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press Landemore H (2012) Democratic Reason: Politics, Collective Intelligence, and the Rule of the Many. Princeton: Princeton University Press Lister A (2005) Hume and Rawls on the Circumstances and Priority of Justice. History of Political Thought 26(4): 664-695 Lucas J (1989) On Justice. Oxford: Clarendon Press Okin SM (1989) Justice, Gender and the Family. New York: Basic Books Parfit D (1986) Reasons and Persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press Rawls J (1999a) A Theory of Justice (revised ed). Cambridge: Harvard University Press Rawls J (1999b) Justice as fairness. In: Rawls J Collected Papers. Harvard, Ma.: Harvard University Press, pp. 47-72 Rawls J (1999c) Justice as reciprocity. In: Rawls J Collected Papers. Harvard, Ma.: Harvard University Press, pp. 190-224 Rawls J (1999d) Reply to Alexander and Musgrave. In: Rawls J Collected Papers, Harvard, Ma.: Harvard University Press, pp. 232-253 Rawls J (1999e) A Kantian conception of equality. In: Rawls J Collected Papers. Harvard, Ma.: Harvard University Press, pp. 254-266 Rawls J (1999f) Kantian constructivism in moral theory. In: Rawls J Collected Papers. Harvard, Ma.: Harvard University Press, pp. 303-58 Rawls J (2001[2003]) Justice as Fairness: a restatement. Harvard, Belknap Press Rawls J (1993[2005]) Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press Sandel M (1982) Liberalism and the Limits of Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press Schwartz Porzecanski D (2004) Friendship and the Circumstances of Justice according to Aquinas, The Review of Politics 66(1): 35-54 Schwartz Porzecanski D (2007) Aquinas on friendship. Oxford: Oxford University Press 31 Sobel C (1972) The need for coercion. In: Pennock, J. and Chapman, J. (eds) NOMOS, vol. xiv: Coercion, Chicago, Atherton Press, pp. 148-177 Tebble, A. J., Epistemic liberalism: a defence, London, Routledge, 2016 Vanderschraaf, P. (2006) The circumstances of justice. Politics, Philosophy & Economics 5(3): 321- 351 Waldon, J., (1999) Law and Disagreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press i I would like to thank Robin Douglass and the two anonymous reviewers at EJPT for their extremely helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper. ii H. L. A. Hart’s account of the five ‘elementary truths concerning human beings, their natural environment and aims’ that provide the basis of the ‘minimum content of natural law’(1994:1293), it has been claimed, bears much resemblance to the standard account. iii A third condition that Hume sets out - although it is not one that all commentators think is essential to his account - is that of our rough equality of moral powers. On this see Hume (1995:§152). iv See also Hope (2010:128-330) and Vanderschraaf (2006:329-30) who highlight the limited property rights and promise-keeping scope of Hume’s account. v For a discussion of this distinction insofar as it relates to Sandel’s critique of Rawls’ account of the circumstances of justice, see Caney (1991:515-16). vi Similarly, and along with a few other objective conditions, Rawls also follows Hume in claiming that we are roughly similar in our physical and mental powers. vii See also Badhwar (1993:7). viii On the relationship between Rawls and Hume on the circumstances of justice, see Lister (2005:664-695). ix With respect to Hume we may note the discussions of Broad and Vanderschraaf. Broad (2009:94-9) is concerned with his objection to Hume’s wider moral theory and not to the cogency of his account of the circumstances of justice per se. Arguing from a game theoretic perspective, Vanderschraaf (2006) claims that Hume’s three conditions are neither necessary nor sufficient for justice because moderate scarcity, confined generosity and rough equality of human powers also obtain in Hobbes’ state of nature where, crucially, there is no justice. 32 x On altruists’ dilemmas see Lucas (1989:49-50); Parfit (1986); Sobel (1972:148-177). xi For a discussion of complex systems in nature see Hayek (1982:I, 39-40). xii For an insightful discussion see Waldron (1999), chapter 7. xiii But see Hope (2010) who defends Hume against Cohen’s critique by distinguishing between the circumstances and the criteria of justice. xiv Hélène Landemore’s defence of democratic rule on epistemic grounds being the most recent example. On this see Landemore (2012). Badhwar NK (1993) The Circumstances of Justice: Pluralism, Community, and Friendship. Journal of Political Philosophy 1(3): 250-276 work_7izrekubs5agxbhvyw7m6cxabe ---- PII: S0022-5223(99)70414-9 For physicians, medical malpractice also means they must maintain costly liability insurance that is out of proportion to that of any other profession. This egre- gious expense is primarily needed to protect against unjustified claims resulting from recognized complica- tions of treating difficult illnesses. The root of the prob- lem is the legal morass that includes an overabundance of attorneys looking for any opportunity to make a buck and an out-of-control civil justice system that allows the pursuit of unmerited allegations. The pinnacle of the absurd is reached if a case ends up in civil court. Here, juries who are not prepared to make judgments about scientifically and technically complex issues are sub- jected to days of theater in which the attorney with the best acting skills is likely to prevail. This occasionally culminates in an overinflated multi-million dollar award, much of which is granted for noneconomic loss- es such as pain, suffering, and loss of consortium. Finally, defensive medicine, a by-product of the threat of malpractice liability, wastes valuable resources to ensure one’s backside is covered. The cost of this prac- tice may be substantial. Patients’ perspective. Patients’ views of the medical liability system differ considerably from those of the physician. What if a patient is injured while undergoing medical treatment and the injury was the result of a mis- take? In such a case, a malpractice claim may be the only way the patient can recoup damages for the injury. I t would be difficult to find anyone who is satisfiedwith the current system of resolving medical liability disputes. In approaching this subject, I have first tried to look at the issues from the perspective of each of the major constituents. Perspectives on medical liability Physicians’ perspective. Physicians take an allegation of malpractice as a personal affront to their profession- alism. It is an attack on their character and dedication, as well as their skill. A claim becomes an emotionally exhausting event for many doctors, and they may end up obsessed with defending their honor. At the extreme, competent doctors have decided to “hang it up” rather than continue their practice in an environment that would allow such an unfair event to occur. 211 From the Department of Cardiothoracic Surgery, University of Southern California School of Medicine, Los Angeles, Calif. Read at the Twenty-fourth Annual Meeting of The Western Thoracic Surgical Association, Whistler, British Columbia, June 24-27, 1998. Received for publication Oct 12, 1998; accepted for publication Oct 13, 1998. Address for reprints: Winfield J. Wells, MD, Department of Cardio- thoracic Surgery, Childrens Hospital Los Angeles, 4650 Sunset Blvd, MS 66, Los Angeles, CA 90027. J Thorac Cardiovasc Surg 1999;117:211-9 Copyright © 1999 by Mosby, Inc. 0022-5223/99 $8.00 + 0 12/6/95153 The Journal of THORACIC AND CARDIOVASCULAR SURGERY PRESIDENTIAL ADDRESS AND JUSTICE FOR WHOM? Winfield J. Wells, MD Volume 117 Number 2 February 1999 Funds may be needed to aid in the patient’s recovery or, in the case of a permanent disability, for long-term care. There is also the issue of lost earnings. Most patients who file a malpractice claim are angry and want to see their doctors punished for the uncaring, incompetent, and potentially dangerous individuals that they are. By suing, they may prevent the same thing from happening to others. The system is a way of getting bad doctors out in the open to be judged and “found out.” While not an enjoyable process, somebody has to do it because the medical profession does a very poor job of policing itself. There is a widely held perception that physicians will not say anything negative about other physicians, particularly if there are potential liability issues involved. This “code of silence” necessitates the need for clever attorneys who can find the truth. The legal perspective. Attorneys and the civil justice system look at medical malpractice in the same way they do any other situation in which a person is injured. That person may be entitled to damages. Why should the health care system be treated differently from oth- ers? Society had established rules and a method for deciding whether there is fault and how much payment should be made if a person is injured as a result of neg- ligence. The civil justice system may be imperfect, but no one has put forward an alternative that “the people” believe would be more fair. The legal perspective might also propose that the malpractice system helps to curtail bad care by high- lighting incompetence. The threat of liability helps keep physicians and the system on its toes, and danger- ous practice is quickly corrected. Attorneys could point out that contrary to what physi- cians and the health care industry might lead the public to believe, the number of malpractice claims is not exces- sive. In fact, many more people are entitled to compensa- tion than ever receive it. The primary platform for this argument comes from two widely quoted reports from the Harvard School of Public Health1,2 that looked at malpractice claims and adverse events due to negligence. These retrospective reviews of randomly selected records of hospitalized patients from the state of New York ini- tially screened more than 30,000 charts, and nearly 8000 were referred to a physician panel for review. From these charts 1100 adverse events were identified. These repre- sented injuries resulting from the patient’s medical care rather than from the primary illness. Among these adverse events, 280 were deemed to be due to negligence. By extrapolation, the authors concluded that about 1% of hospitalized patients had an adverse event resulting from negligence. During the same time period, the number of claims generated per hospital discharge was calculated to be 0.13%. Among the 280 study cases in which negli- gence was suspected, only 8 claims were actually filed (2.8% of potential claims). Not surprisingly, the authors of this study concluded that medical malpractice litiga- tion infrequently compensated patients injured by negli- gence and rarely identified and held providers account- able for substandard care. Overview of medical malpractice involving cardiothoracic surgeons Little information exists on the number of malprac- tice claims filed against cardiothoracic surgeons, the nature and outcome of such cases, and the costs involved. While I was serving as chair of medical-legal affairs for The Society of Thoracic Surgeons (STS), our committee established a relationship with the Physician Insurers Association of America (PIAA). PIAA is a trade association of physician-owned and -operated medical malpractice insurance companies that has been collecting data on malpractice claims since 1985. The PIAA membership includes more than 60 carriers rep- resenting about 240,000 private practicing physicians in the United States and almost 500,000 practitioners abroad. There are currently more than 140,000 closed claims from the United States in the ongoing database, of which 3800 are attributed to cardiothoracic sur- geons. The analysis described in this section comes from a review of these 3800 cases. The PIAA research department estimates that the data-sharing project cap- tures approximately 25% of the claims against privately practicing physicians in the United States. Malpractice claims against cardiothoracic sur- geons. Cardiothoracic surgeons account for about 3% of the malpractice claims in the PIAA closed case file. They are responsible for a relatively smaller percent- age, 2.2%, of all indemnity payments. 212 Wells The Journal of Thoracic and Cardiovascular Surgery February 1999 Fig 1. Natural history of malpractice claims against cardio- thoracic surgeons, based on approximately 3800 closed claims in the PIAA database (1985-1997). Natural history of malpractice claims against car- diothoracic surgeons. The outcome of the 3800 closed claims against cardiothoracic surgeons documented in the PIAA database between 1985 and 1997 has been reviewed. For the purposes of this analysis, there are three potential outcomes: (1) A claim is abandoned, withdrawn, or dismissed (subsequently to be labeled as dismissed); (2) the claim is settled before a verdict at trial; or (3) the claim is resolved by a jury verdict. A few cases were resolved by arbitration, but the numbers were too small for a meaningful analysis. Using the three criteria for outcome, 70% of the claims analyzed were dismissed, 23% were settled, and only 7% were resolved by a verdict at trial (Fig 1). Further, the percentage of claims that were resolved with compensation to the plaintiff over the period 1985-1997 showed no significant trend in either direc- tion over time, with approximately 25% requiring pay- ment. This outcome is similar to the results for the overall universe of all subspecialties covered by the PIAA data wherein 68% of claims are dismissed. Expenditures associated with various outcomes of claims against cardiothoracic surgeons. In general, the expenditures related to a claim have been separated into the dollars spent on managing the defense (ie, attorneys’ fees, fees for expert reviews, fees for deposi- tions) and, if applicable, the dollars paid in indemnity. The expenditures for each of the three potential out- comes have been separately studied, and the trend in costs over a 10-year time period comparing the years The Journal of Thoracic and Cardiovascular Surgery Volume 117, Number 2 Wells 213 Fig 2. Claims that are withdrawn or dismissed (70% of all cases). Average and median expense for defense (in 1998 dollars). Fig 3. Claims that are settled (23% of all cases). Total costs: expense for defense plus indemnity (all in 1998 dollars). 1985-1987 to the years 1995-1997 have been calculat- ed. All expenditures have been converted to 1998 dol- lars by means of a coefficient based on the rate of infla- tion as measured by the Consumers Price Index. Expenditures for claims that are dismissed (Fig 2). Although 70% of claims filed against cardiothoracic surgeons are eventually abandoned, withdrawn, or dis- missed, there are still significant expenses incurred for defense. Among 644 claims that were dismissed in the time period 1995-1997, the average cost per claim was $10,664 and the median cost was $3733. Among 544 claims from 1985-1987, the average was $5860 and the median $2394. All costs have been converted to 1998 dollars. Thus, over a 10-year time period, the average cost to defend a claim that is eventually dismissed has risen 82% and the median cost, 56%. These figures do not account for the substantial time that the accused surgeon often spends on his or her own defense. Expenditures for claims that are settled without a jury verdict (Fig 3). For cases that are settled there are two sources of cost: the expense of defending the claim and the indemnity payment for damages. Although the indemnity portion makes up 85% of the total expendi- ture, the cost of defense for these claims is much high- er than for claims that are dismissed. Among 181 claims that were settled in the period 1995-1997, the average defense cost was $31,742 and the median was $19,081. The total cost of these claims was much higher, with the average among the 181 cases being $242,790, while the median was $119,970. The difference between the aver- age and median costs suggests a skew toward several claims with very high indemnity payments. 214 Wells The Journal of Thoracic and Cardiovascular Surgery February 1999 Fig 4. A comparison of expense for defense between cases that are dismissed, settled, or tried. Average and medi- an for 1995-1997 (all in 1998 dollars). Fig 5. Indemnity payments. Cases settled versus plaintiff verdict (all in 1998 dollars). When these 1995-1997 figures are compared with the costs from 206 cases settled between 1985-1987, a sig- nificant increase in cost is apparent (even after account- ing for inflation). Average costs increased 42% overall, with average defense expenses going up 98% and aver- age indemnity payments increasing 38%. The same analysis for median costs showed an 81% increase overall and 70% and 83% rises for defense and indem- nity payments, respectively. Expenditures for claims that result in a jury ver- dict. This analysis has two arms with one related to cases in which there is a verdict for the defense and the other, those in which the plaintiff prevails. Among the 264 cases resolved at trial between 1985 and 1997, 86% resulted in a defense verdict and in 14% the plain- tiff was awarded damages. As might be expected, the cost of defending a claim that goes to trial is consider- ably higher than for cases that are settled. The average is about twice as much and the median about three times the cost. Whether the case is defended or lost at trial, the cost for the defense is about the same. The average and median costs for defense for claims that are dismissed, settled, and resolved at trial in the peri- od 1995-1997 are compared in Fig 4. The high costs of trial suggest the reason that insurance companies are often anxious to settle claims quickly for a figure that approaches the “cost of defense.” This may be the case even if there is no evidence of practice that is below the standard. Although convenient and seemingly good business practice for the carrier, such settlements may encourage plaintiff’s attorneys to pursue cases involv- ing a maloccurrence, even if no negligence is apparent, in hopes of a quick pay day. Insurance companies con- front a major dilemma in positioning themselves with such “nuisance suits,” and some have elected to defend when expert review suggests no breach of the standard The Journal of Thoracic and Cardiovascular Surgery Volume 117, Number 2 Wells 215 Fig 6. Conditions leading to claims against cardiothoracic surgeons with the percentage of each category where indemnity was paid, and the average payment in dollars. CAD, Coronary artery disease. Fig 7. WTSA malpractice survey: type of coverage. Table I. Claims involving cardiothoracic surgeons by misadventure (1985-1997) Misadventure Percent paid Average (n = 3560) Percent to close indemnity Improper performance 36 28 $174,571 No misadventure 25 6 $197,458 Error in diagnosis 11 27 $161,073 Failure to monitor care 7 30 $181,869 Foreign body 5 45 $30,294 Not indicated 4 31 $164,596 Failure to diagnose 4 28 $182,309 complications Delay in performance 3 32 $212,209 Not performed 3 35 $183,090 Medication error 2 37 $267,612 of care. Although initially more costly, this strategy may be more cost effective in the long run. Finally, there is the matter of indemnity payments for cases that result in a jury verdict for the plaintiff. The number of cases available for analysis is relatively small (n = 37) and the range of awards is large, making it dif- ficult to assess whether there has been a significant upward trend in damages over the period 1985-1997. However, when compared with indemnity payments for cases that are settled, damages awarded by a jury are two to three times higher (Fig 5). There may well have been an attempt to settle these cases, but at a value deemed inadequate by the plaintiff. It should be remembered that the plaintiff’s attorney does take a significant risk when going to trial, since according to the analysis of PIAA data, the chance of prevailing is only about 15%. Cardiothoracic surgery versus other subspecial- ties: Indemnity payments. Overall experience from 1985 to 1997 shows that the average indemnity expen- diture per file requiring payment was $162,584 for car- diothoracic surgery claims. Of the 27 specialties recog- nized by PIAA, cardiothoracic surgery ranked ninth, with specialties like neurosurgery, obstetrics-gynecolo- gy, cardiology, and anesthesia being higher. As an example, the average expenditure per paid file for neu- rosurgery was about $235,000. Conditions that result in claims against cardiotho- racic surgeons. The PIAA database has grouped claims into general categories by type of disease. Not surprisingly, the majority of cardiothoracic surgery claims, 54%, are related to coronary artery disease, which has been arbitrarily subdivided into coronary atherosclerosis, acute infarction, and chronic ischemia. Aortic aneurysm and peripheral vascular problems comprise other higher incidence conditions. Fig 6 sum- marizes the information on the conditions that most often lead to claims, including data on the percentage of such claims requiring indemnity payment and the average indemnity paid. Type of misadventure resulting in claims against cardiothoracic surgeons. The Data Sharing Project has also arbitrarily catalogued the nature of the prob- lems resulting in claims against our specialty. As might be expected, the most common alleged misadventure was “improper performance of a procedure,” which accounted for 35% of closed claims. It is notable that in 25% the insurer could identify “no misadventure,” yet a few of these cases had to be settled anyway. Table I tabulates the relative incidence of misadventures and 216 Wells The Journal of Thoracic and Cardiovascular Surgery February 1999 Fig 8. WTSA malpractice survey: frequency of suits/years in practice. Fig 9. WTSA malpractice survey: malpractice claims by type of care. reports the percentage of such claims requiring indem- nity payment, as well as the average cost. Malpractice experience among members of The Western Thoracic Surgical Association (WTSA) With the idea of obtaining a “snapshot” of medical malpractice in the western part of the United States and Canada, we have surveyed members of the WTSA to learn of their experience. Of 384 active and senior members surveyed, 173 responded (45%). There was proportionate representation from each of the states included in the WTSA’s region, although a large num- ber of the respondents were from California where the majority of our members practice. The median respondent to our survey has been in practice between 20 and 29 years. Although the type of malpractice coverage spanned the options (as depicted in Fig 7), a significant number, 28%, were insured through the institution or university where they were employed. This is probably an aberration of the acade- mic skew common to several of our societies. The median cost of malpractice coverage for all respon- dents was between $20,000 and $25,000, which reflects the relatively high proportion of respondents in academic practice and the fact that the majority were from California, where tort reform has helped reduce premiums. More than 75% of those responding to our survey had been sued, and the average number of suits per sur- geon was two. When we compared the average number of suits with the number of decades in practice (Fig 8), we found no significant difference except that among those practicing for 40 years or more, the incidence was lower. We were unsure whether these more senior respondents had practiced, at least in part, in a “kinder” era, or whether they had just forgotten some of their earlier experience. Fig 9 shows the incidence of mal- practice claims by type of operation and is roughly pro- portional to the incidence of cases done in our subspe- cialty. A further breakdown of claims generated by spe- cific types of patients in the general thoracic and car- diovascular categories is seen in Fig 10. When the outcomes of cases from this WTSA survey are compared with those reported by the PIAA, which has a more national scope, the results are less favor- able. One half of cases reported in the WTSA survey were dismissed or abandoned, whereas in the PIAA experience 70% had that outcome. Only 7% of PIAA cases went to trial, as compared with 17% in the WTSA experience. It is difficult to know whether this means that plaintiff’s attorneys in the WTSA region are more discriminating in selecting cases or more effec- tive in their pursuit. The WTSA survey also showed that among 149 cases that were dismissed, only about one third involved sig- nificant discovery, suggesting the overall cost for these claims should have been relatively low. Likewise, in 40% of the cases that were settled, the settlement cost was less than $30,000, which has traditionally been a threshold for getting rid of nuisance cases that might otherwise involve significant defense costs. These find- ings are shown in Fig 11. Finally, although the number of cases lost at trial was small (n = 19), only 5 (~25%) involved payment of more then $250,000. This may be a reflection of the Medical Injury Compensation Reform Act (MICRA) tort reform legislation, which has been in place in California since 1976. Among other provisions, MICRA limits noneconomic damages (eg, those for pain, suffering, and loss of consortium) to a maximum of $250,000. The expert witness issue A surprisingly large number of respondents to the WTSA survey had served as an expert witness. It could be argued that the responses were biased toward those interested in medical-legal issues, but the fact remains The Journal of Thoracic and Cardiovascular Surgery Volume 117, Number 2 Wells 217 Fig 10. WTSA malpractice survey: malpractice claims by type of care. CABG, Coronary artery bypass grafting. that the percentage was high. In an effort to keep the survey short, we did not get information on how fre- quently opinions had been given for the defense versus the plaintiff. Whereas physicians who read cases for the defense draw little attention from their colleagues, case review for a plaintiff’s attorney triggers animosity from one’s peers. This became acutely apparent to me when, as chair of medical-legal affairs for the STS, our commit- tee attempted to establish a national registry of cardio- thoracic surgery experts. We elicited an amazingly large response from STS members who were willing to have their names made available. A preliminary reg- istry, which was regionalized and categorized by area of expertise (ie, general thoracic, adult cardiac, con- genital), was formed. From the outset the committee believed it was critical that the registry be open to any attorney, whether representing the defense or the plain- tiff. The individual registry experts would determine the acceptability of cases, as well as the fee schedule. When the proposal to implement the registry was put before the STS Council, a small but vocal group defeat- ed the proposal by arguing that allowing plaintiff’s attor- neys access to registry experts would in essence “aid the enemy.” This seemed a shortsighted and unfortunate out- come, because there is no doubt in my mind that there is more benefit than risk in reviewing cases for the plaintiff. This opinion is based on several observations: 1. Plaintiff ’s attorneys have a difficult time obtaining qualified experts in cardiothoracic surgery. Because of the stigmata associated with working for the plaintiff, there is often difficulty in finding a reputable, experi- enced, unbiased surgeon to review a matter. Instead, the plaintiff often ends up with a “hired gun” who finds a way to support even the weakest argument for practice below the standard. That is, after all, in the best inter- est of a professional witness. It is likely that such an expert encourages the continuation of a legal action that might otherwise have been turned down had the plaintiff’s attorney had the benefit of a reputable opin- ion. This phenomenon may also account for the low percentage of plaintiff’s verdicts at trial. 2. An experienced plaintiff ’s attorney does not want to pursue a case without merit. If a reputable unbiased expert reviews a case and finds practice that meets the standard, the vast majority of skilled plaintiff’s attor- neys will drop the matter. We know that a very high percentage of malpractice cases are dismissed, aban- doned, or withdrawn, and it is highly probable that such cases might not have been filed had the plaintiff had access to a reliable expert. It must be conceded that not all attorneys representing the plaintiff are capable and experienced, but as a rule the capable attorneys get the major cases. 3. If a case is below the standard it should be settled quickly. There is the perception that physicians con- spire to protect each other under a “code of silence” even if practice is substandard. This is clearly unac- ceptable, and we as surgeons must not provide the ammunition for such an argument by denying plaintiffs access to experts in our subspecialty. In the majority of instances in which a case is reviewed by a reputable, experienced, unbiased expert and care below the stan- dard is found, settlement discussions begin rapidly. This is as it should be. Valuable resources should not be wasted because the plaintiff cannot find a qualified sur- geon to consider a case. 4. Credibility. Finally, it is difficult to accept a med- 218 Wells The Journal of Thoracic and Cardiovascular Surgery February 1999 Fig 11. WTSA malpractice survey: outcome of malpractice claims. ical expert as unbiased if he or she has only read cases for the defense. In sworn testimony all experts will be asked about their history regarding cases reviewed for the defense versus the plaintiff. A reasonable balance is required to be viewed as impartial. In summary, those involved in medical-legal review should consider plaintiffs’ cases. This will help to build the credibility of our profession and on balance be ben- eficial to our colleagues. Avoiding malpractice suits. In closing, I would like to reflect on the issue of avoiding malpractice suits. The message, like most things that are true, is one that you have heard repeatedly: develop a close, caring rela- tionship with your patients. Patients do not sue physi- cians if they trust them, believe that they care, and believe that everything possible has been done in their best interest. Physicians who have avoided lawsuits are not necessarily the most technically gifted, diagnosti- cally astute, or even the most respected among their peers. They are instead the ones who take the extra time to listen and who organize their practice to show respect for their patients’ time and dignity. The mani- festations of such a practice have been articulated by a group of experienced, suit-free physicians from Texas who made the following suggestions3: 1. Listen patiently. 2. Respect the patient’s dignity and privacy. 3. Return phone calls promptly. 4. Be polite. 5. Be on time. 6. Have the patient join in decision making. 7. Keep patients’ expectations in line with reality (prepare them for all eventualities). 8. Be honest about a misadventure (never cover up or try to blame others). 9. Avoid high-risk situations such as cases you are not fully equipped to handle or cases in which there is a personality clash with a patient or family. 10. Treat the patient as you would like to be treated. We would all be well served to remember and follow this sage advice. I gratefully acknowledge the contribution of Ms Lori Bartholomew in collecting and analyzing data from the PIAA database. R E F E R E N C E S 1. Weiler PC, Hiatt HH, Newhouse JP, Johnson WG, Brennan TA, Leape LL. A measure of malpractice: medical injury, malpractice litigation, and patient compensation. Cambridge [MA], London, United Kingdom. Harvard University Press; 1993. 2. Localio AR, Lowthers AG, Brennan TA, Laird NM, Herbert LE, Weiler PC, et al. Relations between malpractice claims and adverse events due to negligence: results of the Harvard Medical Practice Study III. N Engl J Med 1991;325:245-51. 3. Rosenfield H. Silent violence, sudden death: the hidden epidem- ic of medical malpractice. A consumer guide to the medical mal- practice epidemic. Washington [DC]. Essential Books; 1994. The Journal of Thoracic and Cardiovascular Surgery Volume 117, Number 2 Wells 219 work_7kd2kdtn2za5bkugnopgwakmgu ---- FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, AND JUSTICE* FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, AND JUSTICE* SALLY S. SIMPSON University of Maryland Feminist research has expanded beyond its origins in Women’s Studies to influence the more traditionally bounded academic disciplines. Crimi- nology has not been immune to these excursions. This paper presents an overview of feminist theory/methods and its applications within select areas of crime and justice studies. Points of intra-theoretical divergence as well as directions for future feminist contributions are noted. “WHY CAN’T A WOMAN BE MORE LIKE A MAN?” One is tempted to respond to Henry Higgins’s familiar lament with a cyni- cal observation: criminological theory assumes a woman is like a man. As many feminist-criminologists have noted (early critics include Heidensohn, 1968; Klein, 1973; and Smart, 1976), most middle-range and macro theories of crime generously assume that what is true for the gander is true for the goose (see also Harris, 1977). As tempting as this simple assertion might be, however, a closer inspection reveals a more complicated picture. Some feminist critics (Daly and Chesney-Lind, 1988) suggest that criminol- ogy, like other social sciences, is androcentric, that is, study of crime and the justice process is shaped by male experiences and understandings of the social world. Such studiedrealities form the core of “general” theories of crime/ deviance without taking female experience, as crime participant or victim, into account: [Men] create the world from their own point of view, which then becomes the truth to be described . . . Power to create the world from one’s point of view is power in its male form (MacKinnon, 1982:23). Not all criminological research has ignored women, but all too often, pre- 1970s research on female offenders and victims of crime fell prey to unreflect- ing sexism and, in its more extreme form, misogyny. Females who deviated from expected roles were viewed as morally corrupt, hysterical, diseased, manipulative, and devious (Glueck and Glueck, 1934). Law-violating and -conforming behaviors were believed to stem from the same etiological source-the female nature (Edwards, 1985; Klein, 1973).1 A woman, it * My thanks to Kathleen Daly, Nicole Hahn Rafter, and N . Craig Smith for their insightful comments on a draft of this paper. I was assisted in my revisions by the criticisms of three anonymous reviewers. All of the above are to be commended for their assistance, but none is responsible for the ideas and arguments contained herein. 1. This is not to suggest that biological reductionism is absent in studiedtheories of male criminality. Such explanations of male crime abound (e.g., Wilson and Herrnstein, 1985). However, with the demise of phrenology, social factors replaced biology as key CRIMINOLOGY VOLUME 27 NUMBER 4 1989 605 606 SIMPSON seemed-whether good or bad-could never be like a man. These observations are not new, but they reflect a different voice, a feminist voice, that has been added to the criminological discourse. The purpose of this review essay is to introduce feminist criminology and its intellectual par- ent, feminism, to the uninitiated reader. It would be presumptuous to suggest that all relevant studies and arguments about gender and crime are included here. Such an extensive review is more appropriate for a book, and depend- ing on the topic, it has likely already been done and done well (e.g., Eaton, 1986; Freedman, 1981; Heidensohn, 1985; Mann, 1984; Naffine, 1988; Smart, 1976). Instead, illustrative examples of different types of feminist thinking are presented to show how feminism has reframed our points of reference, underlying assumptions, and understandings about crime, victimization, and the justice process. To achieve these aims, the paper is organized into three sections. First, the perspectives and methods that constitute feminist analysis are sorted and dif- ferentiated. Second, three areas of criminological study (the female offender, female victim, and criminal justice processing) are discussed because they are key areas in which feminist approaches have been incorporated. Third, direc- tions for further integration are suggested. FEMINISM: PERSPECTIVES AND METHODS Feminism is best understood as both a world view and a social movement that encompasses assumptions and beliefs about the origins and consequences of gendered social organization as well as strategic directions and actions for social change. As such, feminism is both analytical and empirical. In its incipient form, feminist research almost exclusively focused on women-as a way of placing women at the center of inquiry and building a base of knowl- edge. As it has matured, feminism has become more encompassing, taking into account the gendered understanding of all aspects of human culture and relationships (Stacey and Thorne, 1985:305). It would be a mistake, however, to think of feminism as a single theory. Feminism has expanded into a diverse set of perspectives and agendas, each based on different definitions of the “problem,” competing conceptions of the origins and mechanisms of gender inequality/oppression, and divergent strat- egies for its eradication. Collectively, these perspectives share a concern with identifying and representing women’s interests, interests judged to be insuffi- ciently represented and accommodated within the mainstream (Oakley, 1981:335). etiological forces. These explanations have not been seriously challenged. Conversely, until the feminist critique of the 197Os, biogenic/psychogenic models of female crime went, for the most part, unchallenged. FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, A N D JUSTICE 607 LIBERAL FEMINISM Liberal feminism was conceived within a liberal-bourgeois tradition that called for women’s equality of opportunity and freedom of choice (Eisenstein, 1981). For the most part, liberal feminists see gender inequality2 emerging from the creation of separate and distinct spheres of influence and traditional attitudes about the appropriate role of men and women in society (Pateman, 1987). Such attitudes are reinforced by discrimination against women in edu- cation, the work place, politics, and other public arenas. Liberals do not believe the system to be inherently unequal; discrimination is not systemic. Rather, men and women can work together to “andro- gynize” gender roles (i.e., blend male and female traits and characteristics; Bem, 1974) and eliminate outdated policies and practices that discriminate against women. Affirmative action, the equal rights amendment, and other equal opportunity laws/policies are advocated as redistributive measures until a meritocratic gender restructuring of society occurs. SOCIALIST FEMINISM For socialists, gender oppression is an obvious feature of capitalist societies. Depending on whether one is a socialist woman (Marxist-feminist) or a socialist-feminist, however, the weight that one gives to capitalism as a neces- sary and/or sufficient cause of that oppression will vary (Eisenstein, 1979). If one is the former, gender (and race) oppression is seen as secondary to and reflective of class oppression. Socialist-feminists attempt a synthesis between two systems of domination, class and patriarchy (male supremacy). Both relations of production and reproduction are structured by capitalist patriarchy (Beauvoir, 1960; Hart- mann, 1979; Mitchell, 197 1). Gender. difference, as a defining characteristic of power and privilege in a capitalist society can only be attacked by con- structing a completely different society, one that is free of gender and class stratification (Oakley, 1981). RADICAL FEMINISM The origins of patriarchy, and the subordination of women therein, are seen by radical feminists to rest in male aggression and control of women’s sexuality. Men are inherently more aggressive than women, who, because of Phillips (1987) argues that the choice of terms describing gender relations imply particular views of what the problem is. So, inequality (a term favored by liberals and some women of color) suggests that women deserve what men and/or whites are granted. Oppression (socialists and women of color) implies a complex combination of forces (ideo- logical, political, and economic) that keep woman in her place. Subordination is a term favored by radical feminists and some women of color who identify the holder of power as the culprit (men and whites respectively). 2. 608 SIMPSON their relative size disadvantages and dependency on men during child-bearing years, are easy to dominate and control. The arguments of radical feminists (e.g., Atkinson, 1974; Barry, 1979; Firestone, 1970; Rich, 1980) bring sexual- ity to the analytical fore. The “personal” is “political” (Millett, 1971). Sex not gender is the crucial analytical category; male domination, not class, is the fundamental origin of female subordination. Radical feminists’ political and social agendas encompass lesbian separatism (Atkinson, 1984) and tech- nological control of reproduction (Firestone, 1970). WOMEN OF COLOR In her eloquent “Ain’t I a woman” speech, Sojourner Truth (1851) informed white suffragists of their myopia about race by highlighting how as a black woman her experience was different from theirs. Joseph and Lewis (1981) remind us that Truth’s commentary is no less relevant today. Many women of color see the women’s liberation movement as hopelessly white and middle class, immune to their concerns. As Hooks (1987:62) observed, Most people in the United States think of feminism . . . as a movement that aims to make women the social equals of men. . . . Since men are not equals in white supremacist, capitalist, patriarchal class structure, which men do women want to be equal to? The alternative frameworks developed by women of color heighten femi- nism’s sensitivity to the complex interplay of gender, class, and race oppres- sion. Patriarchy permeates the lives of minority women, but it does not take the same form that it does for whites (Brittan and Maynard, 1984). Though these contributions may not have coalesced yet into a coherent theoretical framework (at least according to Jagger and Rothenberg, 1984), radical (Lorde, 1988), socialist (Mullins, 1986), and Marxist (Davis, 1981) women of color have provided possible points of integration with theories of race oppression (e.g., Joseph, 1981a, 1981b; Wellman, 1977). In sum, feminist theory is not one perspective; it is a cacophony of com- ment and criticism “concerned with demystifying masculine knowledge as objective knowledge” (Brittan and Maynard, 1984:2 10) and offering insights from a women’s perspective. FEMINIST METHODS The male epistemological stance, which corresponds to the world it cre- ates, is objectivity; the ostensibly uninvolved stance, the view from a dis- tance and from no particular perspective, apparently transparent to its reality. It does not comprehend its own perspectivity, does not recognize what it sees as subject like itself, or that the way it apprehends its world is a form of its subjection and presupposes it (MacKinnon (1982:23-24). Concern over the nonobjective consequences of so-called objective normal FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, AND JUSTICE 609 science (Kuhn, 1970) has led some feminists to challenge the scientific enter- prise. Keller (1982) arranges these challenges on a political spectrum from slightly left of center (liberal feminists) to the more radical left. The liberal critique takes an equal employment opportunity approach by observing the relative absence of women from the scientific community. This view “in no way conflicts either with traditional conceptions of science or with current liberal, egalitarian politics” (p. 114). From this point, however, the criticisms become increasingly fundamental to the way knowledge is produced; they range from charges of bias in select- ing research topics and interpreting results to rejecting rationality and objec- tivity as purely male products. More radical feminists have adopted a methodological strategy that is in direct opposition to the scientific method. In order to “see” women’s existence (which has been invisible to objective scientific methods) “feminist women must deliberately and courageously inte- grate . . . their own experiences of oppression and discrimination . . . into the research process” (Miles, 1983: 12 1). Feminist methods are necessarily subjec- tivist, transdisciplinary, nonhierarchical, and empowering. Where one falls along Keller’s feminist-political spectrum will determine one’s choice of methods (i.e., quantitative versus qualitative) and whether one sees methods and theory as interrelated as opposed to separate and distinct. Thus, methods used by feminists are more diverse than typically credited (for examples, see Jayarate, 1983; Reinhartz, 1983; Stacey and Thorne, 1985). Together, the above theoretical and methodological points form a feminist perspective. All have been incorporated into criminology, but some have had a greater impact than others. The goal in the next section is to identify the ways in which these approaches and methods have changed the way criminol- ogists address the problems of crime and justice. INCORPORATING THE FRAMEWORKS T H E FEMALE OFFENDER The stirrings of feminist criminology are nearly two decades old. Heiden- sohn (1968: 17 l), in a “pre-feminist” paper, bemoaned the state of knowledge about female deviance and called for a “crash programme of research which telescopes decades of comparable studies of males.” Later, Klein (1973) and Smart (1976) were to bring explicitly feminist perspectives to their critiques of extant theoretical and empirical work on the female offender. Klein, a Marxist-feminist, noted the absence of economic and other social explana- tions for female crime. Smart, working within more of a radical feminist per- spective, stressed the linkages among sexist theory, patriarchy, and sexism in practice-specifically identifying the relationship between stereotypical assumptions about the causes of female crime and how female offenders are controlled and treated. 610 SIMPSON Both Klein and Smart set an agenda for a new feminist criminology, but their more radical approaches were derailed by the publication of Simon’s Women and Crime and F. Adler’s Sisters in Crime (1975). Claiming that a “new” female offender was emerging (white collar and/or male like), Simon and Adler generated tremendous interest in female crime (a clear aim of incipient feminism). But, tying the female offender’s emergence to women’s liberation brought about a “moral panic” (Smart, 1976), which was viewed by some as a blacklash to the women’s movement.3 In Chesney-Lind’s (1980:29) words, it represented “another in a century long series of symbolic attempts to keep women subordinate to men by threatening those who aspire for equal- ity with the images of the witch, the bitch, and the whore.”4 As with many social problems of our day, female crime became interesting only when it transcended the expected boundaries of class, race, and gender. As a “quasi-theory,” the liberation-crime relationship had great appeal for nonfeminist crimino1ogists.s But tests of the thesis were less than supportive. In fact most discredited it (Austin, 1982; Giordano et al., 1981), and others found evidence of a link between female crime and economic marginalization (Datesman and Scarpitti, 1980; Gora, 1982; Mukherjee and Fitzgerald, 198 1; Steffensmeier, 1978, 1981; Steffensmeier and Cobb, 1981). The new female offender identified by Simon and Adler was more myth than reality (Steffen- smeier, 1978). These conclusions did not differ substantially from Klein’s (1973), yet they came years after her original critique-a fact that dramati- cally illustrates the marginality of feminist criminology at the time. Yet, sub- sequent research on the causes of female crime has clearly buttressed the economic/class perspectives of Marxist/socialist feminists as well as the 3. The links between women’s liberation and changing patterns of female criminality were made before. Bishop (1931) complained that women’s liberation during the 1920s had three negative results: ( I ) more women were turning criminal; (2) a “better” class of women were becoming criminal more often; and (3) women were becoming sexually crimi- nal at a younger age (cited in Rasche, 1974). T o be fair, both Simon and Adler had more to offer than mere speculation about the “dark side” of women’s liberation. Simon’s research documents the basic inequities between male and female correctional facilities and treatments. By attributing these differ- ences to male chivalry toward women, she takes a liberal feminist approach to the problem of gender and justice, an approach that heavily influenced later works in this area. Adler’s work, while more impressionistic than Simon’s, attempted to explain differences in crime rates between white and black females. Although her interpretations gave rise to more systematic examinations of intra-gender race differences in crime that are highly critical of her interpretations and methods, the issues she raised are of primary importance to most feminist criminologists today. A research focus on gender alone does not qualify one as a feminist just as a focus on class does not make one a marxist. Rather, as part of their endeavor, feminist criminol- ogists must seriously consider the nature of gender relations and the peculiar brand of oppression that patriarchal relations bring (Leonard, 1982). 4. 5 . FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, A N D JUSTICE 61 1 “opportunity” perspectives of the liberal feminists (Ageton, 1983; Box, 1983; Box and Hale, 1984; Elliott and Ageton, 1980; Giordano et al., 1981). In retrospect, feminist criminology both gained and lost from the narrow focus on liberation and crime. On the plus side, we gained a better insight into the historical (Mukherjee and Fitzgerald, 198 1) and cross-cultural (F. Adler, 1981; Plenska, 1980) patterns of female crime. But because the libera- tion thesis was so limited, it diverted attention from the material and struc- tural forces that shape women’s lives and experiences. It is in these areas that women of color and socialist and radical feminist criminologists are more apt to focus etiological attention (Hagan et al., 1985, 1987; Lewis, 1981; Miller, 1985; Rafter and Natalizia, 1981; Wilson, 1985). WOMEN VICTIMS: T H E RADICAL FEMINIST CRITIQUE Liberal feminism has dominated studies of the female offender, but the same is not true of victimology (Daly and Chesney-Lind, 1988). Shifting away from analyses that blame the victim for her victimization (Amir, 1967),6 radical feminists have constructed alternative interpretations of offender-victim relationships and victim experiences of criminal justice (Chapman and Gates, 1978; Klein, 1981; Wood, 1981). Brownmiller’s (1975) historical and cross-cultural study of rape brought a radical feminist perspective to the center of public consciousness. Building on the argument that rape is not a crime of sex but rather an act of power and dominance (Greer, 1970), Brownmiller concluded that rape is a tool in the arsenal of all men to control all women. Radical feminists have reframed the ways in which rape is commonly understood in our society. Rather than a crime of sex, it is more apt to be viewed as one of male power, control, and domination. Brownmiller’s work, coupled with that of other radical feminists (e.g., Griffin, 1979; Riger and Gordon, 1981), opened a floodgate of inquiry into rape and other types of victimizations that are “uniquely feminine” (Wilson, 1985:4), such as pornog- raphy (Dworkin, 1981), battering (Dobash and Dobash, 1979; Martin, 1976; Straus et al., 1980), incest (Finkelhor, 1979; Moyer, 1985; Stanko, 1985) and sexual harassment (MacKinnon, 1979; Stanko, 1985). Guiding much of this research is the radical feminist critique of official conceptions and definitions of violence, which are viewed as male centered and incapable of incorporating the full range of female experiences of violence (i.e., from intimidation and coercion to physical violence and death). A woman-centered definition of violence is one that portrays violence as a form 6 . Precipitous behavior has ranged from dressing provacatively, saying no to sex while “meaning” yes, “nagging” a spouse, Lolita-like seductiveness on the part of the vic- tim, and so on. 612 SIMPSON of social domination rather than a random and/or noninstrumental form of expression (Hanmer, 1981:32). Radical feminists have dominated but not monopolized feminist perspec- tives in this area. Socialist feminists, liberals, and women of color have also participated in the dialogue. Gordon’s (1988) research of family violence is implicitly critical of some radical feminists’ overly deterministic conception of patriarchy. Such an image, she argues, denies agency to women and can- not incorporate “the chronic conflict, unpredictability, and ambivalent emo- tions that have characterized relations between the sexes” (xi-xii). In another historical study, Tomes (1 978) links variations in spousal abuse to changes in the economic position of the working class generally and the male’s position within the family specifically. As the working class improved its economic position and males cemented greater power within their families, the official incidence of working-class battering decreased. Based on her findings, Tomes argues that feminists may need to reconcep- tualize the relationship among male power, female economic dependency, and battering. Dependency is not necessarily tied to greater abuse; in fact, the opposite may be true. A wife’s economic independence may exert a greater challenge to male authority within the family, thus creating a climate in which husbands resort to battering as a means to reestablish their control. Studies that find great variety in the cross-cultural prevalence and inci- dence of rape and battering (e.g., Pagelow, 1981; Sanday, 1981) have forced feminists to examine patriarchal relations across different societal and situa- tional arrangements (e.g., Wilson, 1985). If female victimization is a function of changing the needs of a capitalist/patriarchal system, then male domina- tion and its relationship to female victimization need not be viewed as inevita- ble or immutable. Around the themes of rape and control of sexuality, patriarchy and racism marry and divorce in intricate ways (Davis, 1981). In the United States, white racism and fear gave rise to mythological constructions of black sexual- ity. Black males are perceived as sexual threats and have been hunted and hanged for their “rape potential.” For black victims of rape, the justice pro- cess is not simply gendered-it is racially gendered. Data indicate that black- on-black rapes are not taken as seriously by authorities as those that involve white victims (Kleck, 1981; LaFree, 1980). Such findings have led one prom- inent black scholar (Joseph, 1981b:27) to comment, “It must be considered an impossibility for white men to rape Black women in the eyes of justice and in the minds of many. Black women apparently are considered as something other than ‘women.’ ” GENDER AND JUSTICE PROCESSING A final area to be discussed in this literature review is gendered justice. FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, A N D JUSTICE 613 Comedian Richard Pryor once called attention to discrimination in the U.S. criminal justice system by defining justice as “just us.” His concern with differential sentencing practices is one shared by feminists who primarily study the conditions under which criminal justice is gendered and with what consequences. Although liberal approaches typically dominate the gender- and-justice research, other feminist perspectives are gaining ground-spe- cially in research on courts and corrections. There are many stages in the criminal justice system at which gender may have an impact on decision making. The findings of some of the better- known studies of several strategic points in the decision-making process are summarized below. POLICE Arguments about whether and how justice is gendered must begin with police behavior. That police decisions to arrest can be influenced by extrale- gal factors such as the demeanor of the offender (Black, 1980), has been established. It is less clear how gender, either alone or in conjunction with other characteristics, may consciously or inadvertently influence police behavior. In the liberal “equal treatment” tradition, Moyer and White (1981) test police bias in response decisions under “probable” responses to hypothetical situations. Neither gender nor race had an effect on police behavior once crime type, especially as it interacts with demeanor of the offender, was con- trolled. On the other hand, Freyerhern’s (1981) comparison of juvenile male and female probabilities of transition from self-report incident to police con- tact and arrest, finds males to be more likely to incur police contact and arrest than females. Both of these studies are methodologically problematic, how- ever. Moyer and White cannot generalize their findings to real police encounters and Freyerhern (198 1 :90) does not calculate transition probabili- ties across individual offense categories, nor does he include status offenses. Avoiding some of these methodological traps but still working within a lib- eral tradition, Visher (1983) finds the interaction between race and gender to be a key factor influencing arrest decision. Visher finds police chivalry only toward white females once “legal” factors are controlled. She hypothesizes that black females are treated more harshly than their white counterparts because they are less apt to display expected (i.e., traditional) gender behav- iors and characteristics when they encounter a mostly white and male police force. Race and gender are also found to interact through victim characteristics (Smith et al.. 1984). An analysis of 272 police-citizen encounters, in which both a suspected offender and victim were present, revealed that white female victims received more preferential treatment from police than black female 614 SIMPSON victims. Thus, although chivalry may be alive and well for white women, it appears to be dead (if it ever existed) for blacks. COURTS Police contact is not the only point in justice processing at which discrimi- nation can occur. Women have been found to receive more lenient treatment in the early stages of court processing (i.e., bail, release on own recognizance, and/or cash alternatives to bail; I. Nagel, 1983) and further into the process, e.g., conviction and sentencing (Bernstein et al., 1977; S. Nagel and Weitz- man, 1972; Simon, 1975). Other studies find no gender bias when controlling for crime seriousness and prior record (Farrington and Morris, 1983) or little effect from extralegal factors when legal factors and bench bias are controlled (I. Nagel, 1983). Variation in sentencing may be related to so-called counter- type offenses, that is, women are treated more harshly when processed for nontraditional female crimes, like assault (Bernstein et al., 1977; S. Nagel and Weitzman, 1972), or when they violate female sexual norms (Chesney-Lind, 1973; Schlossman and Wallach, 1978). Given variable-specification problems, however, some of these findings are potentially spurious. Once again, race may confound these effects. Spohn et al. (1982) address the issue of paternalism in sentencing, especially for black women. Control- ling for prior record and attorney type, they found that black women are incarcerated significantly less often than black men, but about as often as white men. They conclude that the apparently lenient treatment of black women is not due to paternalism in their favor but rather to the racial dis- crimination against black vis-a-vis white men. Studies of court processing are not entirely dominated by liberal perspec- tives. More critical perspectives emphasize social power and patriarchal con- trol as the primary mechanisms through which justice is gendered (Kruttschnitt, 1982, 1984). Eaton (1986:35) argues that magistrate courts in Great Britain (the lower courts) reinforce the dominant imagery of justice (i.e., courts are ostensibly fair and just) while they maintain the status quo: “It is in these courts that the formal rules of society-the laws-are endorsed; it is here, too, that the informal, unwritten rules regulating social relations [e.g., gender, class, and race] are re-enacted.’’ When are females apt to be subjected to formal mechanisms of control? When other, more informal, constraints are lacking or disrupted. Kruttschnitt (1982, 1984) suggests that sentencing outcomes are affected by a woman’s social status and/or her respectability. Differential sentencing among women is tied to the degree to which women are subjected to formal versus informal social control in their everyday lives. Daly (1987a, 1989b) and Eaton (1986, 1987) offer convincing evidence that the most important factor determining sentence outcome, once prior record FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, A N D JUSTICE 615 and offense seriousness are controlled, is marital and/or familial status.’ Marital status.has been found to matter for women (married receive more lenient sentences) but not for men (Farrington and Morris, 1983; I. Nagel, 1981) or to be as important for both (Daly, 1987a, 1987b). Pretrial release and sentencing are seen to be both “familied” and “gendered.” They are familied in that court decisions regarding the removal of men and women from families “elicit different concerns from the court” (Daly 1987a:154). They are gendered in that women’s care of others and male economic support for families represent “different types of dependencies in family life” (p. 154). Men and women without family responsibilities are treated similarly, but more harshly than familied men and women. Women with families, however, are treated with the greatest degree of leniency due to “the differing social costs arising from separating them from their families” (Daly, 1987b3287). The economic role played by familied men can, more eas- ily, be covered by state entitlement programs, but it is putatively more diffi- cult to replace the functional role of familied women. Judges rationalize such sentencing disparities as necessary for keeping families together (Daly, 1989b). As these latter studies suggest, much of the observed gender bias in processing may not be a case of overt discrimination for or against women relative to men. Instead, judicial decisions may be influenced by broader soci- etal concerns about protecting nuclear families (Daly, 1989b) and the differ- ing roles and responsibilities contained therein (Eaton, 1986). It is not clear that such forms of justice are overtly paternalistic, nor are they necessarily racist. Rather, in a society that stratifies other rights and privileges by gen- der, race, and class, “equality” in sentencing may not be just (Daly, 1989a). Eaton (1986: 10-1 1) takes a somewhat different view of familied justice. In her opinion, the courts reflect the needs and interests of patriarchy and capi- talism, in which attendant inequities are reproduced. “Family-based” justice is a visible manifestation of the patriarchal and capitalist need to maintain and protect the nuclear family-within which gender and productive/repro- ductive relations first emerge. CORRECTIONS As it became clear that, compared with males, female prisoners were treated differently (in some cases more leniently and in others more harshly), liberal feminist perspectives came to dominate research questions and policy considerations (see, Haft, 1980; Heide, 1974; Simon, 1975). The linkages between female incarceration and male control of female sex- uality are developed by radical feminists (Chesney-Lind, 1973; Smart, 1976). Rasche (1 974), for example, describes how prostitutes with venereal disease These effects appear to be strongest for black defendants (Daly, 1989a). 7. 616 SIMPSON were prosecuted and institutionalized, with the “cure” as a condition of release. Nondiseased prostitutes were less likely to go to jail or prison. Cer- tain prison practices, such as checking for evidence of a hymen during forced physical examinations and vaginal contraband searches, have been used as techniques to control the sexuality of youthful offenders and to humiliate and degrade female inmates (Burkhart, 1973; Chesney-Lind, 1986). Socialist feminists emphasize how prison tenure and treatment vary by class and race (Freedman, 1981; French, 1977, 1978; Lewis, 1981; Rafter, 1985). In her historical accounting of the development of women’s prisons, Rafter (1985155) observes how race determined whether and where a woman was sent to prison. Comparison of incarceration rates and in-prison treatment of black women and white women demonstrates that partiality was extended mainly to whites. Chivalry filtered them out of the prison system, help- ing to create the even greater racial imbalances among female than male prisoner populations. And partiality toward whites contributed to the development of a bifurcated system, one track custodial and predomi- nantly black, the other reformatory and reserved mainly for whites. The bifurcated system of women’s corrections emerges in part from two competing images of female nature. In one view, women are seen as fragile and immature creatures, more childlike than adult. Consequently, the female offender is perceived as a “fallen woman,” in need of guidance but not a true danger to society (Rasche, 1974). The reformatory is perfectly suited to such an offender. Primarily staffed by reform-minded middle-class women, reformatory training programs emphasized skills that would turn the white, working-class misdemeanants into proper (and class-appropriate) women, that is, good servants or wives (Rafter, 1985:82). In custodial prisons, however, a different archetype dominated. Women’s “dark side,” their inherent evil and immorality (Smart, 1976) shaped prison philosophy. Here, the predominantly black felons (who were perceived as more masculine, more self-centered, volatile, and dangerous) were treated like men-only, given the conditions of their incarceration (i.e., fewness of numbers and at the mercy of violent male offenders), their equality was tanta- mount to brutal treatment and often death (Rafter, 1985:181). The degree to which prisons function as something other than just places of punishment and/or treatment is a popular theme in neo-Marxist literature. Extending this interpretation to women, Marxist-feminists (e.g., Wilson, 1985; Hartz-Karp, 1981) argue that prisons, like other institutions of social control (e.g., mental health facilities), retool deviant women for gender- appropriate roles in capitalist patriarchal societies: If deviant women are more frequently assigned to the mental health sys- tem for social control than to the criminal justice system, it is perhaps FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, A N D JUSTICE 617 because of the superior ability of the mental health system to “re-tool” worn-out or rebellious domestic workers. (Wilson, 1985: 18) Societal control of female deviance serves the needs of capital. When those needs change, so too will the mechanisms and directions of social control.8 In this vein, Carlen (1983) demonstrates how “down, out and disordered” women in Scotland are disciplined through medical and judicial apparatuses. Most of the imprisoned are poor women; many have histories of alcohol and drug abuse, and a large number come from violent homes. These life exper- iences combine, setting into motion a cycle of deviance, imprisonment, and patriarchal and class discipline that is tenacious and defeating: Being seen as neither wholly mad nor wholly bad, [women] are treated to a disciplinary regime where they are actually infantalised at the same time as attempts are made to make them feel guilty about their double, triple, quadruple, or even quintuple refusal of family, work, gender, health, and reason (Carlen, 1983:209). WHERE TO GO FROM HERE? In 1976, Carol Smart suggested a number of topics for feminist research.9 A decade later, feminist criminology has amassed a considerable body of knowledge in most of these areas-so much so in fact that feminists now are more self-critical-especially in the areas of policy and legislative changes (see Daly and Chesney-Lind, 1988). This is a positive step. It suggests not only that a feminist voice is being heard, but that it is loud enough to produce disagreement and intellectual exchange. Nonetheless, certain areas in crimi- nology either have been underexposed or are resistant to feminist concerns. Thus, some new directions for feminist criminology are discussed below.10 RACE AND CRIME Poorly conceived offender self-report surveys provided criminologists with the empirical justification to ignore the race-crime relationship, and the pre- vailing political climate reinforced our myopia. There is enormous risk in ignoring that relationship, however. First, based on more sophisticated crime Cloward and Piven (1979) and Box (1983) assert that female deviance is handled by the medical community, in part, because women are more likely to direct their deviance inward (i.e., they privatize it into self-destructive behaviors, like depression and suicide). Such behavior is conceptualized as sickness (like “hysteria” earlier) and is thus subject to the formal control of the psychiatric community. The relevant topics are the female offender and the attitudes of criminal justice personnel toward her; criminal justice processing; gender and corrections; and the structure and purpose of law. To suggest that feminists need to identify areas “appropriate” for feminist critique implies that knowledge, as currently constructed, is selectively androcentric. I would argue that criminology as a whole, like other academic disciplines, needs a feminist “overhaul.” 8. 9. 10. 618 SIMPSON measures (e.g., National Youth Survey, National Crime Survey, cohort stud- ies), it is clear that the race-crime relationship is an essential one. Second, and not unlike the gender-crime relationship, such reticence leaves the inter- pretive door open to less critical perspectives. Feminist criminologists have great potential in this area, but the data are sparse and problematic and the analytic contributions few. Too often we rely on quantitative studies that dichotomize race into white and black, or the nonwhite category is broadened to include groups other than blacks (see, e.g., Tracy et al., in press). In the former instance, other ethnichacia1 groups are ignored; in the latter, such inclusive categorizations assume etiological and historical/cultural invariance between groups. Clearly, one of the first places for feminists to start is to target women of color for greater research. Available data indicate that there are significant differences between black and white female crime rates (Ageton, 1983; Chilton and Datesman, 1987; Hindelang, 1981; Laub and McDermott, 1985; Mann, 1987; Young, 1980). Simpson (1988), Miller (1985), and Lewis (1981) argue that the unique structural and cultural positioning of black women pro- duces complex cultural typescripts that exert push-pull pressures for crime, pressures that may not exist for white women. Miller’s (1985: 177-178) ethnography of lower-class deviant networks describes how certain types of male and female criminality (e.g., hustling, pimping, and other instrumental crimes) are interdependent in minority com- munities. Female crime also appears to have a group-directed and -enacted dimension (see Young, 1980). The collective nature of such minority offend- ing may stem from the fact that it emerges, in part, from the integrated and extended domestic networks of underclass blacks (Miller, 1985) and from joint participation in gang activities (Campbell, 1984). These observations do not imply, however, that patriarchy is absent from these communities. Male dominance and control are reproduced within interpersonal relationships (not necessarily familial) and embodied in infor- mal organizations, like gangs (Campbell, 1984) and state social service agen- cies. Some female offending can be interpreted as challenging patriarchal control and asserting independence (Campbell, 1984: 135); much can be attributed to both economic necessity and the pull and excitement of street life (Campbell, 1984; Miller, 1985). Female participation in violent crime may stem from abusive relationships between men and women (Browne, 1987; Mann, 1987) and/or the frustration, alienation, and anger that are asso- ciated with racial and class oppression (Simpson, 1988). Research by Hill and Suva1 (1988) suggests that the causes of crime may differ for black and white women, which raises questions about whether cur- rent theories of female crime, including feminist perspectives, are white- female centered. Given the paucity of data on how gender structures rela- tionships within minority communities and families, it is impossible to say. FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, AND JUSTICE 619 More quantitative research is needed on minority groups other than blacks (e.g., Chicanos and other Hispanics, Asians, Native Americans) to establish a better knowledge base, but qualitative studies that probe culture and subjec- tive differences between women of color and whites are also essential (Mul- lins, 1986). Feminist criminologists are guilty of the “add race and stir” shortsightedness that pervades feminist thinking. We would do well t o heed Spelman’s (1988:166) reminder of how to understand and approach differ- ences among women: If we assume there are differences among women, but at the same time they are all the same as women, and if we assume the woman part is what we know from looking a t the case of white middle-class women, then we appear to be talking only about white middle-class women. This is how white middle-class privilege is maintained even as we purport to recognize the importance of women’s differences. ELITE CRIME In 1977, Harris admonished criminologists for their failure to use “the sex variable” as the empirical building block for all theories of criminal deviance. Apparently (though not surprisingly) this was interpreted to apply only to street crime. The entire area of white-collar, corporate, and organizational crime has not been examined from a feminist perspective. Officially, women are underrepresented in white-collar crime data although recent Bureau of Justice Sfatistics (1987) data suggest that women have made inroads into this formerly male domain. Similar claims are made regarding female penetration of the upper reaches of organized crime (Simpson, 1987). Yet, Daly (1988) finds neither the crime types nor the offenders themselves to be particularly elite. Much of our information on female participation in organized crime is anecdotal, derived from the nonsystematic observations of male crime partici- pants. Consequently, there has been little systematic research on women’s penetration of and mobility within illicit markets. The official data on corpo- rate and other white-collar offending are equally problematic (see Reiss and Biderman, 1980). Given that both the data and interpretation/theory in these areas are suspect, feminist researchers must first develop an empirical base with which to answer the following types of questions. Is elite crime a male domain (Steffensmeier, 1983)? What are the motivations and character- istics of women who do participate (Daly, 1988; Zietz, 1981)? How are they similar and different from male offenders (P. Adler, 1985; Block, 1977; Simp- son, 1987)? What explains the official increase in female participation in white-collar offenses? At this point, feminists have barely scratched the surface of the elite crime 620 SIMPSON area. Daly (1988) is providing some direction, but much more needs to be done. DETERRENCE Gender confounds the anticipated relationship between objective sanction risks and criminal activity, that is, given that female sanction risks are low, women should have high rates of law breaking. Yet, as virtually all measures of crime document, the exact opposite is true. This empirical relationship has left deterrence theorists scrambling to make sense of the inconsistency. Richards and Tittle (1 98 1 : 183-1 85) argue that there are at least five lines of reasoning that would predict that women perceive higher levels of risk than do men. Using measures derived from these hypotheses, they find two vari- ables, stakes in conformity and perceptions of visibility, to be highly associ- ated with gender differences in perceived chances of arrest: Women may think that legal sanction is relatively certain because they are more likely to think of themselves as subject to surveillance and gen- eral social sanctions than are men. Their greater relative stakes in con- formity may make deviance more threatening for them, and lead to high sanction risk estimates (p. 196). The social control literature, in general, characterizes female conformity in a stereotypical manner. Conforming females are seen as passive, compliant, and dependent. Instead, Naffine (1988: 13 1) suggests that the conforming women be seen as “involved and engrossed in conventional life. But . . . also actively concerned about the effects of her behavior on her loved ones, partic- ularly emotionally and financially dependent children.” (Naffine is especially critical of Hagan et al., 1979, 1985, 1987.) Naffine’s image of conformity is partially influenced by Gilligan’s (1982) work in moral development theory. Gilligan’s research discovers that men and women use “a different voice” when they talk about moral responsibility. If the moral calculus of reasoning about crime is different between men and women, Gilligan may have identified a new way of conceptualizing gender differences in (1) perceived threat of sanction and (2) male-female crime rates. According to her theory, men often make moral decisions based on an “ethic of justice,” while women employ a model of decision making based on an “ethic of care.” The former is a more abstract model, expressed as a set of principles defining rights and rules (e.g., Kohlberg, 1981). In the latter, deci- sions are governed by “a psychological logic of relationships, which contrasts with the formal logic of fairness that informs the justice approach” (Gilligan, 1 9 82:73). A woman’s decision to violate the law will depend on her definition of the moral domain (i.e., how will my act affect those around me, those who count FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, A N D JUSTICE 62 1 on me). It is not surprising that in some deterrence studies (Finley and Gras- mick, 1985) women score significantly higher than men on measures of inter- nalized guilt. Because women are responsible for the care of relationships, any act that may result in their removal from that role is apt to produce a tremendous sense of guilt. Guilt may be negated if the needs of the family (for food or other valued items) outweigh the “immorality” of breaking the law to obtain them or if others are available to take on the responsibilities of care. Gilligan’s theory can be used to explain why most women do not violate the law and why they score higher on most measures of deterrence. It can also explain class and race differences in female crime rates. Lower-class and minority women are more apt to find themselves in situations that require a renegotiation of the moral domain and, given their kinship networks, they have a greater chance of finding care substitutes (Miller, 1985). Not surpris- ingly, Finley and Grasmick (1985) report that blacks score lower on certainty and severity of guilt than their white counterparts. Some critics suggest that Gilligan’s findings are biased (she interviewed mostly middle-class students) or that they may be a function of subordinate female social position, not real differences in ethical philosophies (Tronto, n.d.). These are important criticisms that must be addressed before we pro- ceed too enthusiastically. Gilligan’s conceptualization of differences in gen- der-based moral reasoning, however, are an important contribution and warrant further research. CONCLUSION Feminist criminology has changed dramatically since Klein (1 973) and Smart (1976) first called attention to it. Replicating the same political and analytical development as the broader feminist movement, feminist contribu- tions to the study of crime and justice began with more liberal approaches and have recently been giving way to more radical critiques. Liberal feminist dominance rests, in part, in ideological coherence-these approaches corre- spond closely with the ideas and beliefs embodied in most capitalist democra- cies. Thus, liberalism in any form is less threatening and more acceptable than a feminism that questions white, male, and/or capitalist privilege. 1 1 Additionally, liberal feminists speak in the same voice as a majority of social scientists, that is, they are rational, objective, and (typically) quantitative. Consequently, their data and interpretations carry more weight within the scientific community and among their peers. 11. Stacey and Thorne (1985:308) argue that more radical feminist thinking has been marginalized-ghettoized within Marxist sociology, which ensures that feminist thinking has less of a chance to influence mainstream sociological paradigms and research. 622 SIMPSON Though 1iberaVquantitative approaches offer important insights into gen- der as a “variable” problem (Stacey and Thorne, 1985), criminologists need to be more ecumenical in studying gendered society. If we emphasize qualita- tive (e.g., Campbell, 1984; Carlen, 1986; Eaton, 1986; Miller, 1985), historical (Gordon, 1988; Freedman, 1981; Rafter, 1985), and subjectivist (Stacey and Thorne, 1985) approaches in addition to quantitative, the detail and texture of how crime and justice are gendered will lead to richer theory and better criminology. There are areas in criminology into which feminists have only marginally ventured or in which their contributions have been of little consequence. In their review of feminist criminology, Daly and Chesney-Lind (1988512-5 13) discuss the problems that feminists have had building and developing theories of female crime. It is not coincidental that the areas targeted for further research in this paper (e.g., race and crime, elite crime, and deterrence) all focus on this problematic area. Until we can better deal with the empirical complexities of criminal offending, it will be too easy for our critics to dismiss feminist contributions to the study of crime as facile, rhetorical, and/or atheoretical. REFERENCES Adler, Freda 1975 Sisters in Crime: The Rise of the New Female Criminal. New York: 1981 McGraw-Hill. The Incidence of Female Criminality in the Contemporary World. New York: New York University Press. Wheeling and Dealing: An Ethnography of an Upper-Level Drug Dealing and Smuggling Community. New York: Columbia University Press. The dynamics of female delinquency, 1976-1980. Criminology 2 1:555-584. Victim precipitated forcible rape. Journal of Criminal Law, Criminology, and Police Science 58:493-502. Adler, Patricia 1985 Ageton, Suzanne S. Amir, Menachem 1983 1967 Atkinson, Ti-Grace 1974 Radical Feminism and Love. I n Amazon Odyssey. New York: Links Books. Women’s liberation and increases in minor, major, and occupational offenses. Criminology 20:407430. Austin, Roy L. 1982 Barry, Kathleen Beauvoir, Simone de 1979 Female Sexual Slavery. New York: Avon Books. 1960 The Second Sex. London: Four Square Books. FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, A N D JUSTICE 623 Bem, Sandra 1974 The measurement of psychological androgyny. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology 42:155-162. Charge reduction: An intermediary stage in the process of labelling criminal defendants. Social Forces 56:362-384. Bernstein, Ilene Nagel, Edward Kick, Jan Leung, and Barbara Schulz 1977 Bishop, Cecil Black, Donald 1931 Women and Crime. London: Chato and Windus Press. 1980 On the Manners and Customs of the Police. New York: Academic Press. Block, Alan 1977 Aw! Your mother’s in the mafia: Women criminals in progressive New York. Contemporary Crises 15-22, Box, Steven Box, Steven and Chris Hale 1983 Power, Crime, and Mystification. London: Tavistock. 1984 Liberation/emancipation, economic marginalization, or less chivalry: The relevance of three theoretical arguments to female crime patterns in England and Wales, 195 1-1980. Criminology 22:473497. Sexism, Racism and Oppression. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Brittan, Arthur and Mary Maynard Browne, Angela Brownmiller, Susan 1984 1987 When Battered Women Kill. New York: Free Press. 1975 Against Our Will: Men, Women, and Rape. New York: Simon & Schuster. Burkhart, Kathryn Watterson Bureau of Justice Statistics 1973 Women in Prison. Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday. 1987 Special Report: White-collar Crime. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Department of Justice. Campbell, Anne 1984 The Girls in the Gang: A Report from New York City. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Women’s Imprisonment: A Study in Social Contol. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Carlen, Pat 1983 Chapman, Jane Roberts and Margaret Gates (eds.) Chesney-Lind, Meda 1978 The Victimization of Women. Beverly Hills, Calif.: Sage. 1973 1980 Judicial enforcement of the female sex role. Issues in Criminology 8:51-69. Rediscovering Lilith: Misogyny and the “new” female criminal. In Curt Taylor Griffiths and Margot Nance (eds.), The Female Offender. Criminol- ogy Research Centre. Burnaby, B.C.: Simon Fraser University. Women and crime: The female offender. Signs 12:78-96. 1986 624 SIMPSON Chilton, Roland and Susan K. Datesman 1987 Gender, race, and crime: An analysis of urban arrest trends, 1960-1980. Gender and Society 1:152-171. Cloward, Richard A. and Frances Fox Piven 1979 Hidden protest: The channeling of female innovation and resistance. Signs 4:651-669. Daly, Kathleen 1987a 1987b 1988 Discrimination in the criminal courts: Family, gender and the problem of equal treatment. Social Forces 66:152-175. Structure and practice of familial-based justice in a criminal court. Law and Society Review 21:267-290. Gender and varieties of white-collar crime. Revised version of a paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Society of Criminology, Atlanta. Neither conflict nor labeling nor paternalism will suffice: Intersections of race, ethnicity, gender, and family in criminal court decisions. Crime and Delinquency 35:136-168. Rethinking judicial paternalism: Gender, work-family relations, and sentenc- ing. Gender and Society 3:9-36. Feminism and criminology. Justice Quarterly 5: 497-538. 1980 Women, Crime, and Justice. New York: Oxford University Press. 1989a 1989b Daly, Kathleen and Meda Chesney-Lind. 1988 Datesman, Susan K. and Frank R. Scarpitti (eds.) Davis, Angela 1981 Women, Race, and Class. New York: Random House. Dobash, R. Emerson and Russell Dobash 1979 Violence Against Wives: A Case Against the Patriarchy. New York: Free Press. Dworkin, Andrea 1981 Pornography: Men Possessing Women. New York: Perigee Books. Eaton, Mary 1986 Justice for Women? Family, Court, and Social Control. Philadelphia: Open 1987 University Press. The question of bail: Magistrates’ responses to applications for bail on behalf of men and women defendants. I n Pat Carlen and Anne Worrall (eds.), Gender, Crime and Justice. Philadelphia: Open University Press. Women on Trial: A Study of the Female Suspect, Defendant, and Offender in the Criminal Law and Criminal Justice System. Manchester, N.H.: Manchester University Press. Edwards, Susan M. 1985 Eisenstein, Zillah 1979 1981 The Radical Future of Liberal Feminism. New York: Monthly Review Capitalist Patriarchy and the Case for Socialist Feminism. New York: Monthly Review Press. Press. FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, A N D JUSTICE 625 Elliott, Delbert and Suzanne S. Ageton 1980 Reconciling race and class differences in self-reported and official estimates of delinquency. American Sociological Review 45:95-110. Sex, sentencing and reconviction. British Journal of Criminology Farrington, David and Allison Morris 1983 23~229-248. Finkelhor, David Finley, Nancy J. and Harold G. Grasmick Firestone, Shulamith Bantam. Their Sisters’ Keepers: Women’s Prison Reform in America, 1830-1930. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. An assessment of the black female prisoner in the South. Signs 3:483488. The incarcerated black female: The case of social double jeopardy. Journal of Black Studies 8:321-335. Gender differences in delinquency quantity and quality. In Lee H. Bowker (ed.), Women and Crime in America. New York: Macmillan. In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s Development. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. The economics of female criminality: An analysis of police blotters 1890-1975. In Lee H. Bowker (ed.), Women and Crime in America. New York: Macmillian. Five Hundred Delinquent Women. New York: Alfred A. Knopf. The New Female Criminal: Empirical Reality or Social Myth? New York: Praeger. Heroes of Their Own Lives: The Politics and History of Family Violence. New York: Penguin. 1979 Sexually Victimized Children. New York: Free Press. 1985 1970 The Dialectic of Sex: The Case for Feminist Revolution. New York: Gender roles and social control. Sociological Spectrum 5:3 17-330. Freedman, Estelle 1981 French, Laurence 1977 1978 Freyerhern, William 1981 Gilligan, Carol 1982 Giordano, Peggy, Sandra Kerbel, and Sandra Dudley 1981 Glueck, Sheldon and Eleanor Glueck Gora, Joann Gennaro 1934 1982 Gordon, Linda 1988 Greer, Germaine Griffin, Susan Haft, Marilyn G. 1970 The Female Eunuch. New York: McGraw-Hill. 1979 Rape: The Power of Consciousness. San Francisco: Harper & Row. Women in prison: Discriminary practices and some legal solutions. In Susan Datesman and Frank R. Scarpitti (eds.), Women, Crime, and Justice. New York: Oxford University Press. 1980 SIMPSON Hagan, John, A.R. Gillis, and John Simpson 1985 The class structure of gender and delinquency: Toward a power control theory of common delinquent behavior. American Journal of Sociology 90:1151-1l78. Hagan, John, John Simpson, and A.R. Gillis The sexual stratification of social control: A gender-based perspective on crime and delinquency. British Journal of Sociology 30:25-38. Class in the household: A power-control theory of gender and delinquency. American Journal of Sociology 92:788-816. Violence and the Social Control of Women. Feminist Issues 1 : 2 9 4 6 . 1979 1987 Hanmer, Jalna Harris, Anthony R. 1981 1977 Sex and theories of deviance: Toward a functional theory of deviant type- scripts. American Sociological Review 42:3-16. The unhappy marriage of Marxism and feminism: Toward a more progressive union. Capital and Class (Summer): 1-1 3. Women in constraints. In S.K. Mukherjee and Jocelynne A. Scutt (eds.), Women and Crime. Sydney: Australian Institute of Criminology with Allen and Unwin. Hartman, Heida 1979 Hartz-Karp, Janette 1981 Heide, Wilma Scott 1974 Feminism and the “fallen woman”. Criminal Justice and Behavior 1~369-373. Heidensohn, Frances 1968 1985 Women and Crime. London: Macmillan. The deviance of women: A critique and an enquiry. British Journal of Sociology 19:160-175. Hill, Gary D. and Elizabeth M. Suva1 1988 Women, race, and crime. A revised version of a paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Society of Criminology, Chicago. Hindelang, Michael 1981 Variations in sex-race-age-specific incidence rates of offending. American Sociological Review 46:461-474. Feminism: A movement to end sexist oppression. In Anne Phillips (ed.), Feminism and Equality. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. The value of quantitative methodology for feminist research. In Gloria Bowles and Renate Duelli Klein (eds.), Theories of Women’s Studies. Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul. The incompatible menage a trois: Marxism, feminism, and racism. In Lydia Sargent (ed.), Women and Revolution. Boston: South End Press. White promotion, black survival. In Gloria I. Joseph and Jill Lewis (eds.), Common Differences: Conflicts in Black and White Feminist Perspectives. Boston: South End Press. Hooks, Bell 1987 Jayarate, Toby Epstein 1983 Joseph, Gloria I. 1981a 1981b FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, AND JUSTICE 627 Joseph, Gloria I. and Jill Lewis (eds.) Common Differences: Conflicts in Black and White Feminist Perspectives. Boston: South End Press. 198 1 Keller, Evelyn Fox 1982 Feminism and science. In Nannerl 0. Keohane, Michele Z. Rosaldo, and Barbara C. Gelpi (eds.), Feminist Theory. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Klein, Dorie 1973 1981 The etiology of female crime: A review of the literature. Issues in Criminology 8:3-29. Violence against women: Some considerations regarding its causes and its elimination. Crime and Delinquency 27:64-80. The Philosophy of Moral Development. San Francisco: Harper & Row. 1982 Respectable women and the law. The Sociological Quarterly 23:221-234. 1984 Kohlberg, Lawrence Kruttschnitt, Candace 1981 Sex and criminal court dispositions: The unresolved controversy. Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency 21 :213-232. Kuhn, Thomas 1970 The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 2nd ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Laub, John and M. Joan McDermott An analysis of serious crime by young black women. Criminology 23:81-98. Black women offenders and criminal justice: Some theoretical considera- tions. In Marguerite Warren (ed.), Comparing Female and Male Offenders. Beverly Hills, Calif.: Sage. 1985 Lewis, Diane 198 1 MacKinnon, Catherine A. 1979 The Sexual Harassment of Working Women. New Haven: Yale University Press. 1982 Feminism, Marxism, method, and the state: An agenda for theory. In Nannerl 0. Keohane, Michele Z. Rosaldo, and Barbara C. Gelpi (eds.), Feminist Theory, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Female Crime and Delinquency. Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press. Black female homicide in the United States. Paper presented at the Conference on Black Homicide and Public Health, Baltimore. Mann, Coramae Richey 1984 1987 Martin, Del Miles, Maria 1976 Battered Wives. New York: Pocket Books/Simon & Schuster. 1983 Toward a methodology for feminist research. In Gloria Bowles and Renate Duelli Klein (eds.), Theories of Women’s Studies. Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Street Woman. Philadelphia: Temple University Press. Miller, Eleanor M. 1985 628 SIMPSON Millett, Kate Mitchell, Juliet 197 1 Sexual Politics. London: Rupert Hart-Davis. 1971 Woman’s Estate. New York: Random House. Moyer, Imogene L. 1985 The Changing Roles of Women in the Criminal Justice System: Offenders, Victims, and Professionals. Prospect Heights, Ill.: Waveland Press. Police processing of female offenders. I n Lee H. Bowker (ed.), Women and Crime in America. New York: Macmillan. Moyer, Imogene L. and Garland F. White 1981 Mukherjee, S.K. and R.W. Fitzgerald 1981 The myth of rising female crime. In S.K. Mukherjee and Jocelynne A. Scutt (eds.), Women and Crime. Sydney: Australian Institute of Criminology with Allen and Unwin. Mukherjee, S.K. and Jocelynne A. Scutt (eds.) 1981 Women and Crime. Sydney: Australian Institute of Criminology with Allen and Unwin. Naffine, Ngaire 1988 Female Crime: The Construction of Women in Criminology. Boston: Allen and Unwin. Nagel, Ilene H. 1981 Sex differences in the processing of criminal defendants. In A. Morris and L. Gelsthorpe (eds.), Women and Crime. Cambridge: Cambridge Institute of Criminology. The legal/extra-legal controversy: Judicial decisions in pretrial release. Law and Society Review 17:481-515. Double standard of American justice. Society 9:18-25, 62-63. 1983 Nagel, Stuart and Lenore J. Weitzman Oakley, Ann Pagelow, Mildred 1972 1981 Subject Women. New York: Pantheon. 1981 Sex roles, power, and woman battering. In Lee H. Bowker (ed.), Women and Crime in America. New York: Macmillan. Pateman, Carol 1987 Feminist critiques of the public/private dichotomy. In Anne Phillips (ed.), Feminism and Equality. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. 1987 Feminism and Equality. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Phillips, Anne (ed.) Plenska, Danuta 1980 Women’s criminality in Poland. In Curt Taylor Griffiths and Margot Nance (eds.), The Female Offender. Criminology Research Centre. Burnaby, B.C.: Simon Fraser University. Rafter, Nicole Hahn 1985 Partial Justice: Women in State Prisons, 1800-1935. Boston: Northeastern University Press. FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, AND JUSTICE 629 Rafter, Nicole Hahn and Elena Natalizaia 198 1 Marxist feminist: Implications for criminal justice. Crime and Delinquency 27:81-98. Rasche, Christine 1974 The female offender as an object of criminological research. Criminal Justice and Behavior 1:301-320. Experimental analysis: A contribution to feminist research. In Gloria Bowles and Renate Duelli Klein (eds.), Theories of Women’s Studies. Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Reinhartz, Shulamit 1983 Reiss, Albert J., Jr. and Albert P. Biderman 1980 Data Sources on White-collar Law-Breaking. National Institute of Justice. Washington, D.C.: U.S. Department of Justice. Compulsory heterosexual and lesbian existence. Signs 5:63 1-660. Gender and perceived chances of arrest. Social Forces 59:1182-I 199. The fear of rape: A study in social control. Journal of Social Issues Rich, Adrienne Richards, Pamela and Charles R. Tittle Riger, Stephanie and Margaret T. Gordon 1980 1981 1981 37:71-92. Sanday, Peggy Reeves 1981 The socio-cultural context of rape: A cross-cultural study. The Journal of Social Issues 37:5-27. The crime of precocious sexuality: Female juvenile delinquency in the progressive era. Harvard Educational Review 48:65-94. Women in elite deviance: A grounded theory. Paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Society of Criminology, Montreal. Caste, class, and crime: Violence and the disenfranchised black female. Revised version of a paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Society of Criminology, Chicago. Schlossman, Steven and Stephanie Wallach 1978 Simpson, Sally S. 1987 1988 Simon, Rita Smart, Carol 1975 Women and Crime. Lexington, Mass.: D.C. Heath. 1976 Women, Crime and Criminology: A Feminist Critique. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Equity and discretionary justice: The influence of race on police arrest decisions. Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology 75:234-249. 1988 Inessential Woman: Problems of Exclusion in Feminist Thought. Boston: Smith, Douglas, Christy Visher, and Laura Davidson 1984 Spelman, Elizabeth V. Beacon. The effect of race on sentencing: A re-examination of an unsettled question. Law and Society Review 16:71-88. Spohn, Cassia, John Gruhl, and Susan Welch 1982 630 SIMPSON Stacey, Judith and Barrie Thorne Stanko, Elizabeth A. 1985 The missing feminist revolution in sociology. Social Problems 32:301-3 16. 1985 Intimate Intrusions: Women’s Experience of Male Violence. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Crime and the contemporary woman: An analysis of changing levels of female property crime, 1960-75. Social Forces 57:566584. Patterns of female property crime, 1960-1975: A postscript. In Lee H. Bowker (ed.), Women and Crime in America. New York: Macmillan. Organization properties and sex-segregation in the underworld: Building a sociological theory of sex differences in crime. Social Forces 61:1010-1043. Sex differences in urban arrest patterns, 1934-79. Social Problems 29:37-50. Behind Closed Doors: Violence in the American Family. Garden City, N.Y.: Anchor/Doubleday. A “torrent of abuse”: Crimes of violence between working-class men and women in London, 1840-1875. Journal of Social History 11:328-345. Steffensmeier, Darrell J. 1978 1981 1983 Steffensmeier, Darrell J. and Michael J. Cobb Straus, Murray A., Richard J. Gelles, and Suzanne K. Steinmetz 1981 1980 Tomes, Nancy 1978 Tracy, Paul E., Marvin E. Wolfgang, and Robert M. Figlio Tronto, Joan C. In press Delinquent Careers in Two Birth Cohorts. New York: Plenum Publishing. n.d. “Women’s morality”: Beyond gender difference to a theory of care. Unpublished paper, Hunter College of the City University of New York. Cited in Gloria I. Joseph and Jill Lewis (eds.), Common Differences: Conflicts in Black and White Feminist Perspectives. Boston: South End Press. Truth, Sojourner 1851 Visher, Christy 1983 Gender, police arrest decisions, and notions of chivalry. Criminology 2 15-28, Wellman, David 1977 Portraits of White Racism. New York: Cambridge University Press. Wilson, James Q. and Richard J. Herrnstein Wilson, Nanci Koser 1985 Crime and Human Nature. New York: Simon & Schuster. 1985 Witches, hookers, and others: Societal response to women criminals and victims. Paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Society of Criminology, San Diego. The victim in a forcible rape case: A feminist view. In Lee H. Bowker (ed.), Women and Crime in America. New York: Macmillan. Wood, Pamela 1981 Young, Vernetta D. 1980 Women, race, and crime. Criminology 18:2&34. FEMINIST THEORY, CRIME, A N D JUSTICE 63 1 Zietz, Dorothy 1981 Women Who Embezzle or Defraud: A Study of Convicted Felons. New York: Praeger. Sally S. Simpson is an Assistant Professor of Criminal Justice and Criminology at the University of Maryland, College Park. In addition to her interest in issues of gender and crime, she is currently involved in studies of organizational change and its effects on the ethical dimensions of decision-making. work_7li5lt5dp5ab7f7nfjg3ywg4ti ---- 1 "This is the author's accepted manuscript. The final published version of this work (the version of record) is published by Taylor and Francis in Annals of the Association of American Geographers 2nd January 2018. This work is made available online in accordance with the publisher's policies. Please refer to any applicable terms of use of the publisher." Spatializing climate justice: Justice claim-making and carbon-pricing controversies in Australia Ian Bailey School of Geography, Earth and Environmental Sciences, Plymouth University Abstract: Recent years have seen significant academic attention to conceptualizing climate justice and how its ideas might be mobilized in political debates on climate policy. This article contributes to these debates by advancing two arguments. The first concerns the need for greater examination of how climate justice co-exists and competes with more established political and justice considerations during the negotiation of climate policies. I argue that distinguishing analytically between normative interpretations of climate justice and justice claims made by parties affected by climate change or by mitigation or adaptation policies provides fertile ground for deepening understanding of the multivalent and relational nature of climate justice and confronting challenges to its incorporation into climate responses. The second argument concerns the importance of exploring of how proponents and opponents of climate action strive to develop “spatial anchors” for justice claims to increase their legitimacy in policy debates. Based on analysis of carbon pricing controversies 2 in Australia, the article illustrates how supporters of carbon pricing initiatives stressed international justice issues, while opponents mobilized multi-scalar and multivalent international, national, regional and local justice narratives to gain traction for their arguments. The article concludes by calling for further investigation of the multi-valence of climate justice and of how climate justice might be spatially represented to advance its leverage in political debates on climate policy. Keywords: climate justice, justice claims, carbon pricing, spatial representation, Australia Introduction Justice has formed a major theme in debates on climate change ever since climate issues first began to gain sustained political attention in the 1980s (Meyer and Roser 2010; Bulkeley et al. 2013; Bulkeley, Edwards and Fuller 2014). Over this period, substantial scholarly and political attention has been directed towards conceptualizing the forms of rights, responsibilities, procedures, and distributional outcomes that just responses to climate change might entail and how these might be applied to different issues and social and spatial settings (Backman and Page 2008; Parks and Roberts 2008; Vanderheiden 2008; Roberts and Parks 2009; Bulkeley et al. 2013). These endeavors have led to appreciable progress in understanding the ethical implications and dilemmas raised by climate justice (Shue 1993; Klinsky and Dowlatabati 2009; Klinsky 2015). However, progress towards integrating justice into climate-related decision-making 3 remains faltering. Deeper interrogation of how climate justice is constructed and contested during practical initiatives to mitigate and adapt to climate impacts--where the cross-cutting challenges of climate change for existing political, economic, and social systems are often painfully and acrimoniously manifested--thus remains a priority if climate justice is to progress beyond being an admirable but largely abstract concept (Greer 2014). So far, efforts by climate-justice scholars to address this challenge have been directed mainly at developing normative proposals on how to integrate climate justice into political decision- making through ideas such as contraction and convergence and ecological debt repayment (Gardiner 2006; Page 2008; Roberts and Parks 2009; Gardiner 2011). In contrast, detailed empirical studies of how climate justice contends with other, often more established, justice considerations during the negotiation and implementation of climate policies remain relatively scarce. Without greater understanding of the practical relationship between climate justice and climate policy, however, progress in integrating climate justice into political decision-making on climate issues is likely to remain stymied. This article responds to this agenda by examining how justice is constructed and expressed within debates on national climate policy. National climate politics has been a relatively underexplored area of climate-justice scholarship compared with the international, sub- national and city scales (e.g. Parks and Roberts 2008; Peet and Harrison 2012; Bulkeley et al. 2013; Bulkeley, Edwards and Fuller 2014). However, the importance of nation states to climate policy-making and the mediation of climate justice trade-offs suggests that the national politics of climate justice merit more sustained attention. Two main arguments are proposed. The first concerns a need for deeper examination of how climate justice co-exists and competes with more established political and justice considerations within climate 4 policy. Preoccupation with conceptualizing or applying climate justice principles risks treating climate justice as somehow removed from other political and justice interests. Allied to this is the importance of developing clearer analytical distinctions between normative interpretations of climate justice (its “rightful” role in climate policy) and justice claims, where individuals or groups use justice arguments sincerely or tactically to gain recognition for their interests (Backman and Page 2008; Klinsky 2015). When examining real-world climate politics, climate-justice scholarship must remain alert to the multiple climate and non-climate justice claims mobilized to gain approval for standpoints that might not enjoy support unless attached to some form of justice claim. As such, the first strand of enquiry focuses on how competing multivalent justice claims, articulating diverse values and preferences, shape debates on climate policy (Fraser 2001; Klinsky 2015). The second argument concerns the need for further exploration of the tactics used by different actors to gain political legitimacy for their justice claims. Such tactics might include mobilizing widely-accepted discourses, such as stressing technological innovation or carbon markets over lifestyle constraints (Dryzek 2013), utilization of the media (Gavin 2009), or the personalization of issues by identifying climate-related victims and perpetrators (DiFrancesco and Young 2011). Another tactic of keen interest to geographers is the attachment of socio-spatial representations to justice claims--the linking of justice claims to particular groups located in specific places--to enhance the status of claims in debates on climate action (Walker 2009; Klinsky 2015). For instance, corporations might influence climate policy to a degree by highlighting effects on competitiveness but may boost their influence further by aligning their interests with accepted national concerns about economic growth, or with more geographically-rooted issues, such as risks to employment in regions 5 that depend on the sector if emissions constraints are imposed. Such spatial anchoring of justice narratives provides a powerful technique for personalizing justice claims and making them more relevant and urgent by affiliating them with politicians’ electoral incentives, especially if they are taken up by media outlets and erode public support for climate action (Harrison and Sundstrom 2010). These themes of multivalent justice claims and their socio-spatial anchoring are explored by examining recent debates on carbon pricing in Australia, where claims about national regional and local socio-economic injustices have been defining features of industry, political and public opposition to carbon pricing. Among the prominent claims have been the injustices of introducing carbon pricing in a minor contributor to global emissions like Australia without action by industrializing countries, and discourses stressing the unfairness of imposing carbon pricing on resource-dependent regions in rural Australia, and on households across the country. These socio-spatial injustice claims overshadowed government arguments about Australia’s responsibility to contribute to global mitigation efforts and representations of climate change as a “great moral challenge” (Rudd 2008), and led ultimately to the repeal of carbon pricing in Australia in 2014. Understanding how such socio-spatial justice claims are mobilized and influence climate policy forms a key but largely overlooked dimension of research on justice claim-making in climate politics. The following section considers how climate justice has been articulated, exploring how climate-related rights, responsibilities, distributional equity, and procedural fairness interact and are underpinned by the recognition of justice claims. Within this discussion, emphasis is placed on distinctions between normative views of climate justice and justice claims 6 recognized within debates on climate change, and how claims may be advanced through socio-spatial representations that connect issues and interests to identifiable places and people. The third section outlines the history of carbon pricing in Australia before the fourth section examines how politicians, industry and the media used international, national, regional, and local justice anchorings justice to arouse support or opposition to carbon pricing. The final section explores theoretical and policy implications for understandings of climate justice. Climate justice in context Over the last two decades, scholars across a range of disciplines have explored the principles of climate justice and the justice dilemmas embedded in decision-making on climate policy (Shue 1993; Gardiner 2006; Page 2008; Klinsky and Dowlatabadi 2009; Bulkeley, Edwards and Fuller 2014). While no single justice framework for dividing burdens has emerged (Klinsky, Dowlatabadi and McDaniels 2012), broad agreement exists on the core goals of achieving fairer distributions in rights and responsibilities related to the causes and effects of climate change, spanning mitigation, adaptation, and loss and damages for climate-related harms (Page 2008; Bulkeley et al. 2013). These, however, raise complex questions about temporal, social, and spatial unevenness in greenhouse-gas emissions and vulnerability to the effects of climate change (Hornborg 1998; Gardiner 2006; 2011), while further questions surround procedures for addressing grievances and ensuring representation both for groups affected by climate change and those impacted by climate policies (Lind and Tyler 1988; Shue 1993; Kuehn 2005). MacCoun (2005) and Gross (2007) argue that procedural justice is particularly important where uncertainty exists on what 7 constitutes fair aggregate or distributive outcomes to encourage participation by all relevant parties and open debate on the ethical dimensions of climate decision-making1. While rights, responsibilities, representation, and fair procedures provide the conceptual foundations for specifying more detailed justice principles--such as causal responsibility, preferential treatment based on need, and equity of burdens or effort (Singer 2002; Klinsky and Dowlatabadi 2009)—Bulkeley, Edwards and Fuller (2014, 33) also stress the need for investigation of the contexts in which framings of justice are created. Rather than just analysing principles by which climate justice might operate, they call for sustained empirical examination of the political economies, power relations, and opportunity structures influencing how climate justice is conceived, applied and contested. Central to this, they maintain, is recognition, both for groups as rightful stakeholders entitled to be represented in discussions, and for certain arguments to be considered as justifiable (also Gardiner 2006; Grasso 2010; Schlosberg 2012). As Schlosberg (2004) emphasizes, if legitimate groups or concerns are marginalized by those making executive decisions, procedural fairness, and achieving fair outcomes can be critically compromised. Bulkeley, Edwards and Fuller (2014) conceptualize recognition as forming the critical underpinning of climate rights, responsibilities because of its central role in determining which issues and groups are considered or sidelined in justice debates. They additionally use the metaphor of a prism to emphasize interconnections between the different facets of climate justice and how ideas refract as solutions to justice issues are debated. For instance, recognition of certain rights creates typically creates new responsibilities for other actors that may require new forms of recognition and procedural mechanisms to accommodate 8 redistributions of resources (Shue 1993). In most instances, these interactions require negotiation, leading to modified demands and procedures to find acceptable solutions (Page 2008; Parks and Roberts 2008). This multivalent view of climate justice emphasizing recognition as critical to achieving fair outcomes simultaneously draws attention to distinctions between judgements about what rights, responsibilities, distributions, and procedures should be recognized and those that are accepted in climate debates. Importantly, this shifts the analytical lens from examining recognition chiefly in terms of the ethical and empirical strength of claims towards the capability of individuals and groups to place their values and interests on agendas (Gavin 2009; Walker and Day 2012). Two key considerations arise from this. The first concerns the importance of distinguishing between Rawlsian justice principles and justice claims, where groups seek support for their interests or preferences by framing them as justice concerns (Klinsky 2015). Both entail constructions of distributional and procedural fairness, but focusing on justice claims foregrounds the political reality that responses to climate issues usually impact other interests that enjoy some societal acceptance. These competing claims can take non-commensurable forms and be challenging to adjudicate on ethical grounds (Fiske and Tetlock 1997). Rawls (1972, 340) himself observed that there are often no obvious rules for prioritizing between competing obligations, and doubted “whether a systematic solution formulating useful and practical rules is possible”. Many authors have, nevertheless, explored ethically-defensible ways to address justice dilemmas on climate action. Notable examples include: contraction and convergence that apportions responsibilities through differentiating between luxury and subsistence 9 emissions (Shue 1993; 1999); repayment of ecological debts from developed countries to developing countries caused by financially and ecologically unequal trade relations (Roberts and Parks 2009); fault-based and ability-to-pay approaches (Shue 1993); and distributive justice based on equitable burdens or effort (Heyward 2007; Klinsky and Dowlatabadi 2009). Scrutiny of these approaches is beyond the scope of this article. However, all focus on integrating distributive justice into existing political and economic systems rather than empirically examining how power relations within these systems influence how climate justice competes with other justice considerations to shape climate policy. As such, they maintain a normative rather than an explanatory approach to analyzing political deliberations on the ethics of climate action. The second consideration accordingly focuses on the politics of arbitrating between justice claims. Traditional realist perspectives often downplay the role of justice and emphasize self-interested bargaining and power and resource differentials as determinants of political bargaining within and between nations (Okereke 2010). In national policy contexts, political economy perspectives typically stress access to politicians and officials, finance, media campaigns, and public support as key political resources used by non-government actors to influence decision-makers’ incentives (Pralle 2009; Harrison and Sundstrom 2010). More constructivist writers argue, however, that climate policy outcomes cannot be understood solely through the lenses of power and material interests, and stress the devices used to promote standpoints, including the use of discourses to construct interpretations of the nature of environmental problems and the consequences of different policy solutions (Dryzek 2013). Although not the only discursive framing used to steer the normative context of decision-making on climate change (e.g. ideas of ecological modernization), 10 justice narratives hold particular potency because of their links with instinctive societal values concerning fair or unfair treatment (Walker and Bulkeley 2006). While climate justice can be constructed to appeal to many ethical concerns, the main focus in this article is the use of socio-spatial representations to increase the authenticity of justice claims and their connections with other societal priorities. This affiliation of justice claims to identifiable peoples and places resonates with Opotow's theory of moral exclusion, that claims often receive less weight when interpreted as distant, non-essential, and competing with existing deep-core values and preferences (Klinsky, Dowlatabadi and McDaniels 2012). Pinpointing climate victims and perpetrators--such as floodplain populations in Bangladesh and large U.S. fossil-fuel companies--are obvious examples of spatialized justice arguments in climate advocacy. However, drawing boundaries that distance climate impacts and attribution temporally or spatially but invoke immediacy and proximity in the adverse effects of climate policy can equally generate senses of injustice around policies. Industry groups may also counteract being judged as undeserving claimants by projecting their interests as justice considerations affecting more worthy plaintiffs, such as communities and regions that depend on the sector, while giving the justice claim greater geographical rootedness (Hafer and Olson 2003). Further socio-spatial anchoring of justice claims may invoke justice failings by others. Classic usages of such narratives include: uneven historical contributions to current greenhouse-gas concentrations by the global North and South (Shue 1993); rapid emissions growth among industrializing countries; and the incapacity of low-lying island states to mitigate climate change relative to their vulnerability (Meyer and Roser 2010). Such comparisons can again 11 have multiple motivations, but many countries have portrayed climate change as a collective-action problem to stress the unfairness of accepting excessive mitigation burdens (Bulkeley and Newell 2010). Similarly, corporations and governments may advocate level playing fields in the global economy to defend weak climate measures, whilst unequal burden sharing between rural and urban areas may be cited in debates on siting renewable- energy technologies (Cowell, Bristow and Munday 2011). Multivalence and the socio-spatial anchoring of justice claims thus form critical themes in debates on climate justice. The first is underscored by the reality that, howsoever conceived, climate justice is obliged to compete with other ideas and interests that often incorporate some justice claim, making trade-offs integral to climate decision-making (Klinsky, Dowlatabadi and McDaniels 2012). Similarly, whilst justice claims can utilize multiple framings, the use of socio-spatial representations holds significant potential for legitimating ideas and interests and moving beyond generic principles to situated understandings (Hillman 2006). With this in mind, the following sections summarize the research strategy and the recent history of carbon pricing in Australia before considering how multivalent and spatialized justice claims have influenced policy debates. Research Strategy The first phase of research was conducted in 2010 and analyzed the political arguments and tactics used to debate Australia’s first proposed carbon pricing mechanism, the Carbon Pollution Reduction Scheme (CPRS). The second took place in 2015 and focused on debates on the introduction and repeal of the Clean Energy Future Act Carbon Pricing Mechanism (CPM). Each phase involved analysis of official documents, media reporting and 12 independent commentaries on carbon pricing (550 and 183 documents in phases one and two respectively), and was complemented by semi-structured interviews with politicians, government officials, and industry, academia, non-government organization, and consultancy representatives involved in developing or analyzing the CPRS and/or CPM. Thirty-one interviews were conducted in phase one, with a further twenty interviews in phase two. A summary of the respondent profile is given in Table 1. Texts and interview transcripts were subjected to qualitative content analysis, avoiding affixing pre-conceived categories to the arguments mobilized during the carbon-pricing debates; instead categories emerged inductively from the data (Hsieh and Shannon 2005). Categories were then grouped iteratively into related ideas, drawing on recurring themes in accounts and texts to produce researcher descriptions of the main themes arising from the research (Flowerdew and Martin 2005). Although the research explored the broader arguments and tactics used to debate carbon pricing in Australia, justice emerged as a prominent theme, illustrated by frequent uses of terms such as fairness, inequity, and distribution. Numerous references to international, national, regional, and local issues within these arguments in turn prompted further investigation of how justice was discursively and spatially represented carbon pricing opponents and supporters. Carbon pricing in Australia Australia was an early signatory to the Kyoto Protocol but has struggled to take decisive action to reduce its greenhouse-gas emissions. Most analysts attribute this to the political influence of its major extractive and energy-intensive industries and strong political 13 competition between the Labor Party, Liberal-National Coalition and the Greens on whether and/or in what form to introduce carbon pricing (Pearse 2009; Burgmann and Baer 2012; Christoff 2013; Crowley 2013; Rootes 2014). Under Kyoto, Australia committed to restricting its emissions growth to eight percent above 1990 levels by 2008-2012, but in 2002 the Coalition led by John Howard followed the U.S. in refusing to ratify the Protocol, arguing that it was against Australia’s national interest (Crowley 2007; Lawrence 2009). Throughout the 1990s and 2000s, Australian climate policy instead consisted mainly of voluntary measures that avoided binding emissions targets and sanctions, and it was only in 2007 that Howard commissioned a prime ministerial task force to investigate emissions trading in response to pressure from Labor, which was campaigning for carbon pricing in the 2007 federal election campaign (Rootes 2008). Following a landslide victory, Labor’s new prime minister, Kevin Rudd, made Kyoto ratification his government’s first official act and began preparing a national emissions trading scheme, the Carbon Pollution Reduction Scheme (CPRS), drawing on recommendations made in the first Garnaut Review commissioned by Rudd to study the effects of climate change on Australia and policy options to reduce Australia’s emissions (Garnaut 2008). However, the CPRS model was heavily criticized by the Coalition and industry as damaging to Australia’s energy-intensive trade-exposed industries (EITEIs) without comparable measures by trading partners in Asia and North America, and by the Greens for over-generous compensation to EITEIs. After the CPRS was rejected by the Senate in August 2009, Rudd sought support for the legislation from the Coalition leader, Malcolm Turnbull, who supported carbon pricing but sought greater assistance for EITEIs. 14 However, following Turnbull’s ousting by carbon-pricing opponent Tony Abbott in December 2009, the CPRS again failed in the Senate and was shelved in 2010 (Bailey et al. 2012; Burgmann and Baer 2012; Crowley 2013). Following the CPRS’s failure and other policy debacles, Rudd was replaced by his deputy, Julia Gillard, in June 2010. Gillard wanted to secure her own mandate and called an election for August 2010. Although carbon pricing remained on the government’s agenda, Gillard sought to counteract Coalition successes on the CPRS by promising there would be “no carbon tax under a government I lead”. The 2010 election led to a hung parliament, with the government relying on independents for a majority in the House of Representatives. Additionally, the Greens held the balance of power in the Senate, giving the minority government an unexpected opportunity to introduce carbon pricing by renegotiating with the Greens (Crowley 2013). The Clean Energy Act was adopted in November 2011 despite continued Coalition opposition, creating the Carbon Pricing Mechanism (CPM), an emissions trading scheme covering 300 of Australia’s largest polluters. To secure the Greens’ support, Gillard introduced an initial fixed price of AUS$23 per tonne of carbon (approximately $23.30, December 2011 exchange rate) between 2012 and 2015 before it moved towards flexible pricing by 2018 (Caripis et al. 2011)2. The fixed price was also intended to give industry certainty about their financial exposure but was portrayed as a thinly-disguised tax that betrayed Gillard’s pre-election promises. The Clean Energy Act incorporated further measures to ease burdens on industry and households: a Jobs and Competitiveness Program giving EITEIs free allowances; an Energy Security Fund to help energy generators move 15 towards low-carbon energy; a Clean Technology Program to promote energy-efficient technologies; and a Clean Energy Household Assistance Package of payments, increased income tax thresholds, and tax benefits for low- and middle-income families (Australian Government 2011). However, EITEIs continued to attack the CPM for damaging competitiveness, while Tony Abbott made a “blood oath” to repeal the carbon tax if elected (Gratton and Wroe 2011). Despite Gillard’s replacement as prime minister by her predecessor, Kevin Rudd, in June 2013 and attempts to regain business and voter confidence by announcing that flexible pricing would be introduced a year earlier than planned, the Coalition won the September 2013 election, and in July 2014, Abbott repealed the CPM after securing the support of the Palmer United Party3 in the Senate (Rootes 2014). Justice Claims in Carbon-Pricing Policy in Australia Most accounts of Australian climate policy stress structural features of its political economy (the country’s fossil-fuel dependence) and the industry lobbying power as explanations for Australia’s difficulties in adopting more ambitious mitigation policies (Crowley 2007; Pearse 2009; Rootes 2011; 2014). Although important, these factors provide limited insight on how non-government actors influenced policy, for instance, how industry gained political support for commercial arguments by making them resonate with public or opposition-party concerns. Christoff (2013, 349) provides some insight on this by examining how scientific, ethical, economic, technological, political/legal, and everyday life discourses contribute to the constitution of national climate discourse complexes that “frame and discipline climate debate and the articulation of a national climate policy regime”. Christoff argues that 16 domination of Australia’s climate discourse complex by economic narratives has diminished the influence of scientific, ethical, and other discourses4 on carbon pricing. However, this still underemphasizes limits on the traction of economic pleading and focuses on aggregate patterns in Australian national climate politics rather than the multiple discourses--including ethical discourses about fair treatment to legitimate commercial arguments--that shape broader discourse complexes, empowering or disempowering actors within national climate-policy debates. Before analysing how different justice claims were mobilized and spatialized in debates on carbon pricing in Australia, two points should be stressed. First, the analysis seeks to understand how multivalent socio-spatial constructions of justice have shaped Australian debates on carbon pricing, and so avoids value judgements about the claims made. The second concerns the implicit and often unconscious nature of many justice claims. Arguments about the CPRS and CPM frequently contained justice overtones, such as stressing effects on vulnerable groups, but did not employ justice terminology explicitly or in a premeditated way (Klinsky 2015). Alternatively, some actors invoked justice arguments tactically by projecting their political or commercial interests as justice concerns for other parties to elicit greater sympathy without revealing the preferences and judgements upon which the viewpoints in question were based (Howarth 2009; Dryzek 2013). The core argument within this section is that most opponents of carbon pricing saw the CPRS and CPM as genuinely unjust and/or contrary to their commercial or political interests, but appreciated the fundamental arguments for climate action or the untenability of directly challenging government framings of just climate responses by Australia. Opposition 17 consequently centered on highlighting alternative sets of rights, responsibilities, distributive, or procedural issues. Although many such framings drew on older economic discourses about short-term economic security and its allied welfare benefits (Christoff 2013), they propagated multivalent definitions of what fair rights, responsibilities, distributions, and procedures meant within Australia climate policy to contest mainstream government interpretations. A key device in developing these alternative justice framings was to stress the effects of carbon pricing across a range of recognizable spatial jurisdictions within Australia, from the national to the local, to broaden the range and credibility of injustices employed to oppose carbon pricing and to characterize identifiable victims in order to press for recognition of their rights. International and national justice framings Fairness in the distribution of mitigation responsibilities between Australia and other countries has formed a critical theme throughout Australian debates on carbon pricing. The Howard government’s dominant narrative centered on drawing normative distinctions between imposing burdens on Australia and the climate responsibilities of other countries. This was expressed forcibly when Howard announced that Australia would not ratify the Kyoto Protocol without comparable commitments by major developing countries because he was not prepared to “be party to something that destroys jobs and destroys the competitiveness of Australian industry” (The Age 2003). Such statements earned Howard the reputation of presiding over a decade of neglect on climate change by hawking justice interpretations that pitched global climate justice against national economic concerns and externalized accountability for his government’s reliance on voluntary mitigation (Crowley 2007). 18 The Labor government took a starkly different standpoint. Kevin Rudd repeatedly described climate change as: “the greatest moral, economic and social challenge of our time”, arguing that an affluent country like Australia had an ethical duty to reduce emissions for well-being of other countries threatened by climate change (Rudd 2008). Similarly, the Garnaut Review stressed that the: “problems of unmitigated climate change will be for all humanity” (Garnaut 2008, 592) while also emphasizing the benefits to Australia’s national interest to take action to counter climate risks to the country and to lead in the international marketplace of initiatives to decarbonize the global economy. However, Garnaut did also seek to address distributive issues within Australia by arguing, among other things, for trans-national sectoral agreements for iron and steel, aluminum, chemicals, cement, and paper and pulp to overcome industry relocation and carbon leakage caused by the unequal application of carbon pricing in other countries producing emissions-intensive internationally-traded goods (Garnaut 2008). Despite such efforts, the CPRS and CPM debates steered towards a more multivalent view of distributive justice, emphasizing short-term economic and social impacts, that diluted the traction of global burden-sharing arguments. Although there was broad support from an early stage for global action to counteract fairness concerns, the CPRS’ ambitious design (covering 75 percent of Australian emissions and all six Kyoto greenhouse gases compared with 45 percent coverage of carbon only in Europe) fueled impressions that “Australia was way out in front of other countries” (senior official). International distributive concerns were also fed by early reassurances from the government that “no Australian would be 19 worse off under the CPRS”. One official argued that this created “unrealistic expectations that hardened industry opposition when the CPRS legislation was released”. Further attempts were made to calm competitiveness concerns during the CPM debate when in 2011 the Gillard government instructed the Productivity Commission to assess the burdens of climate policy in other key economies, although it only analyzed energy generation and transport, and only covered competitive pressures affecting EITEIs indirectly (Productivity Commission 2011). Further, the CPM was introduced with the initial fixed price of AUS$23 ($23.30) per tonne of CO2-equivalent--at the time at parity with the EU carbon price--to broker a deal with the Greens, and to give certainty about industry’s liabilities until the market matured. However, any conciliatory effect from these measures foundered when the EU price collapsed in late 2011. One government official recalled being: “inundated with questions about why Australian companies were paying $23 per tonne and European companies were paying $23 per tonne”. Another dimension of international-national injustice narratives was the futility of carbon pricing because of Australia’s relatively modest contribution to global emissions. In his autobiography as opposition leader, Tony Abbott argued that Australia only accounted for one percent of global carbon emissions and that China’s annual increase in emissions could match Australia’s entire carbon output5. According to this logic, action by Australia without agreements by industrializing nations would damage industry but make limited difference to global emissions (Abbott 2009). Extending international comparisons beyond competitiveness (and resonating with Garnaut’s warnings about carbon leakage) shifted the debate further from Australia’s contribution to international environmental and social 20 climate justice towards one focused “almost entirely on domestic economic justice” (industry). Furthermore, framing Australia’s actions as futile diverted attention from ethical responsibilities Australia might have to reduce emissions and, instead, emphasized only the sacrificial elements of carbon pricing. Industry groups used further tactics to portray carbon pricing as an unjust contest between Australian and other national interests. These included a further spin on economic arguments stressing the contribution of resource-intensive sectors to Australia’s resilience to the 2008-2010 global recession and arguments that “what was good for coal was good for Australia” (official). Similarly, a 2013 Australian Industry Group report avoided contravening broader climate-justice concerns by not opposing carbon pricing outright while still promoting justice arguments about securing a fair deal for Australia. The report expressed support for market-based approaches but raised concerns about the CPM compared with carbon prices in other countries during challenging local and global economic conditions (Australian Industry Group 2013). Industry interviewees also recalled frustration at government negotiators comparing climate policies at a national level. As one industry representative argued: This approach was no good for understanding competitive pressures. A facility in one Chinese province may not face a carbon price despite there being a regional or national carbon price because there is a lot of shielding and discrepancy between the national and competitive level. Blanket approaches don’t work. Equally, imposing annual standard reductions in free 21 allowances to EITEIs cannot reflect real-life situations and is not responsive to market shifts. In response, industry associations submitted studies of pressures at the competitive gate comparing the climate policy burdens faced by individual competitor installations to add further dimensions to arguments that Australian companies were being treated unfairly at the international scale (industry). Regional justice and local mining communities While spatial binaries between national and global concerns were a recurring theme in justice claim-making by carbon-pricing opponents, the CPRS and CPM also prompted strident debates on regional justice that led to further targeting and broadening of the justice arguments used to oppose carbon pricing. Much of this focused on securing fair treatment for resource-dependent states like Western Australia and Queensland and mining communities across the country. Among the tactics used was to pinpoint specific regional effects. During the CPM debate, Barnaby Joyce, then Shadow Minister for Regional Australia, Regional Development and Local Government lambasted the government’s treatment of regional Australia: New South Wales [NSW] Treasury figures show that the carbon tax will lead to 31,000 lost jobs in NSW but over 26,000 of these would be in regional Australia, including 18,500 in the Hunter, 7,000 in the Illawarra and 1,000 jobs in the central West… If [the minister] wants to continue his ‘embrace the 22 challenge’ tour of regional Australia he needs to come clean [about] how they are meant to embrace the challenge of fewer employment opportunities… A carbon tax will clearly hurt regional Australia the worst. (Australian Conservative 2011) Industry lobbying also focused attention on specific communities by spotlighting issues facing individual facilities, including Northern power station in South Australia and the Portland and Kurri Kurri aluminum smelters in Victoria and New South Wales (industry and regulator). Although there was no suggestion this tactic was used cynically, it contributed to the diversity of justice arguments used by personalizing the impacts of carbon pricing to generate “victims and villains” stories. Because of regional concentrations in coal mining, the coal sector was particularly active in staking regional injustice claims (official), while regulators recalled energy companies threatening power failures in major cities because: “the carbon price would trigger a huge asset write-off on coal-based assets and a number of generators could go bankrupt”. The latter example offers an interesting demonstration of the growing multivalence of justice claim-making brought about by drawing “innocent bystanders” into the carbon- pricing debate through the idea that it would negatively affect every aspect of people’s lives in cities like Melbourne that rely on coal-fired electricity. Interviewees argued that portrayals of the government failing to protect coal-mining regions and power supplies did not reflect the intensity of consultations with industry or the sophisticated measures introduced to address distributive issues (see Behm (2015) for an insider account of consultations on the CPM). One academic nevertheless noted that a belief among officials 23 that a market instrument would automatically resolve distributive problems caused them to underestimate subnational issues. A senior ex-official and government advisor further recalled that, following consultations, the government often: “thanked associations then closed the door to focus on policy development”. This led to industry feeling marginalized from final decision-making because of the government’s preoccupation with gaining support from key political partners. As one consultant put it: “there was the odd brown-bag discussion, but the government didn’t see business as critical in getting the legislation through”… and this “aggravated industry anger towards the CPM where distributive issues remained unresolved”. In contrast, a senior negotiator argued that: “whatever we did, some sectors always tabled further demands and used Tony Abbott’s attacks on carbon pricing opportunistically to gain leverage”. One crucial feature enabling regional justice arguments to feature so prominently was that, unlike the EU ETS negotiations, the CPRS and CPM debates took place in the full media and political glare. One consultant argued that because that industry: “felt disenfranchised from decision-making, they used the media to present their issues as general voter concerns and to lobby individual electorates”. This tactic again proved potent because it played on longstanding resentment about the neglect of mining and other resource-dependent towns in regional Australia by political elites in Canberra, Sydney, and Melbourne (Botterill 2006; see Peet and Harrison 2012 for similar portrayals of urban-rural political dynamics in British Columbia). In this case, legacies of neglect found two expressions: uneven impacts of carbon pricing on regional households that experience higher car dependence, longer travel distances and more extreme climates; and direct challenges to livelihoods from the possible contraction or closure of major employers in the resources sector. The Australian 24 newspaper provided inflammatory reporting of this issue in a 2011 study for the Australian Coal Association (ACIL Tasman 2011): Explosive economic modelling warns that the carbon tax could force eight black coalmines to close, costing nearly 3000 jobs in regional NSW and more than 1100 jobs in Queensland in its first three years… Independent modelling commissioned by the Australian Coal Association warns that early mine closures could reach 18 within nine years… ACIL Tasman estimates that between 22,700 and 31,020 man-years of jobs will be forgone… Mr Hillman [executive director of the ACA] said: “These are real jobs, supporting real families in regional Australia”. (The Australian 2011, emphasis added). Bacon and Nash (2012) note that media coverage of the carbon-pricing debate exhibited journalistic endorsement across all newspapers of the national and regional economic benefits of coal mining and electricity generation but marked differences in reporting of the sectors’ climate impacts, a perception illustrated by coverage of impacts on marginal electorates, such as Townsville in Queensland, where mining provides around one-third of employment (Speck 2010). Contrasting assessments by the Climate Institute (2011) and other pro-carbon pricing groups, meanwhile, contributed to public perceptions of injustice surrounding the CPRS and CPM from alternative directions, as offering unjust compensation to EITEIs (academic). The characterization of issues and groups were recalled by one regulator involved in media communications: 25 When the CPM came out, it was terrible. We were forced into being very defensive; the media was taking a tabloid approach on cost and the idea that the prime minister lied about not introducing a carbon tax. There were also constant comparisons with actions elsewhere, this myth that Australia was leading the world and it was very difficult to cut through these arguments. But, if we didn’t engage with the media, the CPM would be even attacked even more, but however we tried, we had ‘shock jocks’ [populist radio commentators] and other press on our backs. One issue that struggled to command political attention because of such reporting, despite repeated efforts, was the justice implications of Australia’s vulnerability to climate impacts. The 2008 and 2011 Garnaut Reviews both placed strong emphasis on regional and national climate impacts to strengthen the case for carbon pricing, while Bureau of Meteorology reports routinely stressed threats to water availability, infrastructure, energy systems, urban areas, and terrestrial and marine ecosystems, including the Great Barrier Reef (Cleugh et al. 2011). Although this characterized climate change as an issue worthy of attention and certain areas as under threat, it did not translate into robust public support for carbon pricing (Pietsch and McAllister 2010), not least because of disputing by industry and opposition leaders of links between individual events and climate trends (senior official). As Prime Minister, Tony Abbott characterized reports linking the 2013 Sydney bushfires to climate change as “hogwash”, claiming Australia had always experienced fires and floods (The Guardian 2013a), a view supported by environment minister Greg Hunt (consultant). 26 Such questioning of links between extreme events and climate change and the framing of carbon pricing as conflicting with national and local economic justice arguably compounded the domination of Australia’s climate discourse complex by economic discursive fields that emphasized resource-led short-term growth (Christoff 2013), and forced the Garnaut Review team and other carbon-pricing proponents into defending carbon pricing on these grounds rather than the longer-term economic and social implications of climate change (consultant). Shifting the debate into this economic terrain, meanwhile, further enabled carbon-pricing opponents to emphasize distributive justice by fashioning geographically personalized non-climate justice narratives (Kurz, Augoustinos and Crabb 2010). Justice for households A final arena of justice claim-making in Australian carbon-pricing debates concerned implications for households. John Howard again set the tone for this discussion in 2006 by contrasting equivocal acceptance of climate science with emphasizing a broad range of non- climate justice concerns: the “enormous burden to be carried by consumers through much higher electricity prices, higher petrol prices, falls in GDP, of too dramatic an imposition of what you might call an anti-greenhouse policy.” (Australian Broadcasting Corporation 2006). The characterization of carbon pricing as a multi-pronged injustice against working Australians was intensified by Abbott, who branded the CPRS “a great big tax on everything” and declared the 2013 election a referendum on the carbon tax (academic). As was noted earlier, the political capital gained by these attacks forced Julia Gillard to assert during the 2010 election campaign that there would be: “No carbon tax under a government I lead”, though she maintained throughout that she would introduce carbon pricing (Rootes 2014). 27 In fact, the Gillard government worked energetically to address the CPM’s impact on households. One senior official described how the department was instructed: to track every form of household category to analyze the effects of different carbon prices and their translation into electricity prices, and to scour every element of the tax system to identify where and how households could be assisted so the CPM did not create a financial burden. One independent expert described the Household Assistance Package’s treatment of equity as “outstanding” and “a wonderful analysis”. The official nevertheless conceded that: the package failed because the government decided not to link it to the CPM because the CPM was so unpopular and instead presented the package as a tax gift. It was a political decision to benefit the minority government, but in hindsight the government missed the opportunity to steer public debate towards climate change and the basic reason for carbon pricing. In addition to damage inflicted by Gillard’s decision to introduce an initial fixed price on carbon of AUD $23 per tonne caused by the collapse of EU carbon prices, officials and regulators also recalled several unrelated issues becoming conflated within the growing and increasingly multi-issue narrative of injustice surrounding the CPM. These included the global financial crisis and increases in electricity prices caused by overinvestment in energy infrastructure. Neither was connected to the CPM but coincidences in timing enabled anti- carbon tax campaigners to stir up further unfairness narratives. In addition to Abbott’s 28 sloganeering on the “tax on everything” and Gillard’s carbon tax “lie”, regulators noted provocative remarks by Barnaby Joyce that the Australian Sunday roast would cost AUD$100 (US$101, December 2011), and pledges by the Palmer United Party, a key partner in repealing the CPM in 2014, to refund the tax that it claimed was destroying Australian families (Palmer United Party 2013). Although justice claim-making on behalf of households might be categorized as a social rather than a spatial issue, it has distinctive spatial implications under Australia’s compulsory preferential voting system. This requires voters in each electorate to rank candidates in preference order; if no candidate gains over 50 percent of first preferences, the candidate with the fewest votes is excluded and their votes are reallocated to second preferences until someone achieves a majority. Supporters argue that the system represents all citizens’ views, but opponents argue that it forces voters to support non- preferred candidates and increases safe electorates because voters often rank their non- preferred major party low in their preferences (Evans 2006; Fowler 2013). It also encourages parties to court popularity across a range of issues to maximize preferences gained from eliminations rather than taking a strong stand on individual issues. Compulsory voting also incentivizes targeting of voters with limited interest in politics in marginal electorates rather than the majority whose voting behaviour is guaranteed. The 2013 election saw focused campaigning in the Western Sydney, Melbourne, and Brisbane suburbs, often accompanied by locally-directed expenditure pledges (The Guardian 2013b). Although the government sought to defuse Abbott's attacks by announcing the early introduction of flexible pricing, Abbott claimed this merely replaced an unjust fixed tax with an unfair variable one (Rootes 2014). 29 In summary, developing multiple lines of justice argumentation, especially focusing on the short-term economic and social costs of climate action, and the spatialization of these claims towards discrete socio-spatial scales and locations proved a highly effective weapon in undermining carbon pricing in Australia despite assessments that the impacts of the CPM were substantially mitigated by industry and householder assistance (Meng, Siriwardana and McNeill 2013). In particular, pitching injustice claims about carbon pricing within specified national, regional and local boundaries enabled CPM opponents to reach multiple audiences, influence how issues and groups were characterized, and outmaneuver government attempts to frame carbon pricing as a general global-justice and national- conscience issue. Interestingly, claims about injustices created by the CPM appeared to gain greater political traction than tangible measures to address distributive issues. Most assessments suggest the government provided innovative measures to ameliorate the CPM’s effects on households and regionally concentrated industries. However, its unwillingness to stress links between the household package and climate action underscores the importance of messaging framing and claim-making within debates on climate policy. The government’s failure to generate momentum behind the distributional impacts of climate change on Australia can be again attributed chiefly to the Coalition’s capacity to dispute links between individual events and human impacts in order to recharacterize which issues and groups deserved and did not warrant recognition. Additionally, casting doubt on Australia’s ability to make a difference to global emissions proved useful in magnifying the injustice of imposing burdens on Australian regions and households, whilst simultaneously projecting justice responsibilities towards other countries where action deficits could be identified within the international climate negotiations. 30 Conclusions Australia has witnessed a highly adversarial debate on carbon pricing over the last decade (Rootes 2011; 2014). Although the extent to which this has extended beyond parliamentary and business circles into the media and public debate makes Australia an extreme case, even compared with the U.S., it illustrates many difficulties that can encircle national debates on the justice dimensions of climate policy. Australia’s stalling in introducing decisive policies to reduce its greenhouse-gas emissions is commonly attributed to its fossil- fuel dependency, the lobbying power of resource-intensive industries, and self-interested politics (Pearse 2010; Rootes 2011; Crowley 2013). However, these interpretive lenses provide only a partial insight on how such national and commercial interests gain political traction in the face of scientific, international, and ethical pressure for climate action. Justice perspectives do not hold a monopoly on explanations for the introduction or failure of policies. However, most climate debates involve some discussion of rights, responsibilities, and distributions. As such, critical analysis of justice narratives provides instructive comparative lessons on how perceptions of fairness influence climate agenda setting (Klinsky 2015). This article has advanced two main arguments. The first concerns the need for sustained attention to how climate justice interacts with other forms of justice claim within climate politics. Whilst conceptualizing the principles and parameters of climate justice and how it might be integrated into international negotiations and individual climate initiatives is vital for clarifying the rights, responsibilities, distributions, and procedures affected by climate change, scholars must also engage actively with alternative justice discourses surrounding 31 this topic to help understand and shape trade-offs between climate and non-climate justice claims in climate policy (Christoff 2013). In Australia, the interweaving of multiple justice arguments around climate impacts and the economic and social impacts of carbon pricing was an important contributor to the repeal of the CPM and underscores the reality that different voices appeal to diverse ethical bases and audiences to influence what are accepted as legitimate or unjust responses to climate change (Walker and Shove 2007). Recent work conceptualizing climate justice has stressed its multivalent and evolving character and that: “the politics and practices of… climate change interventions are constantly engaging with and refracting the idea of justice,” (Bulkeley, Edwards and Fuller 2014, 31). However, the Australian case suggests the need to consider two overlapping but distinctive circuits of refraction. The first concerns how climate justice responsibilities, distributions, and procedures interact internally to produce new understandings of the concept and its implications. The second concerns how each component of climate justice interacts with other justice claims, such as freedom of choice and economic livelihoods. In the Australian carbon-pricing debates, few actors openly contested rights of protection from climate impacts, but many still opposed carbon pricing on alternative justice grounds. This more multivalent view of how justice is framed in climate politics accentuates the need to understand each element of justice as a complex of climate and non-climate justice considerations, each with its own dilemmas and trade-offs in how justice principles and claims are prioritized, rather than viewing each solely in terms of climate rights, responsibilities, distributions and procedures (Rawls 1972; Klinsky, Dowlatabadi and McDaniels 2012). Although this further complicates analysis of climate justice by incorporating non-climate justice considerations alongside climate justice, it also creates 32 productive spaces to explore more deeply how conflicts between different sets of rights, responsibilities, distributions, and procedures are mediated during the negotiation of climate initiatives. This emphasis on climate justice claim-making also foregrounds important distinctions between normative ideas about what claims should be recognized and claimants’ capacity to gain recognition for themselves and their arguments (Schlosberg 2004). While all protagonists in the Australian carbon-pricing debate sought to maintain the moral high ground by employing justice-related argumentation, gaining political traction was often determined as much by proficiency in securing recognition as by the substance of arguments (Christoff 2013). In this case, broadening the range of issues deemed to merit consideration and populist sentiments about unfair taxation6 on households and trade- exposed industries gained greater media exposure and recognition than practical packages to address distributive issues. In addition to underscoring the importance of recognition in climate justice debates, such instances raise questions about ensuring procedural fairness where gaining recognition is determined by capabilities rather than normative arguments (Gross 2007). The second argument concerns the attachment of socio-spatial representations to justice claims as a device to enhance recognition by aligning arguments with identifiable places and peoples. Routledge (2011, 384) argues that climate activists might use such spatial framings to draw out “translocal climate justice solidarities” between peoples experiencing climate injustices. However, the Australian carbon-pricing experiences equally illustrated the spatialization of justice claims as a framing device to highlight genuine concerns about 33 regional impacts and to pursue commercial or political interests “in the shadow” of fairness claims (Boykoff 2008). Both sides in the debate used socio-spatial justice representations to strengthen their arguments. However, carbon-pricing opponents proved more skillful in generating spatially- and socially-recognizable discourses about distributional impacts on households and communities in regional Australia, and in constructing selective portrayals of national interests vis-à-vis those of other nations. In contrast, carbon-pricing advocates relied on responsibilities-based representations of Australia’s international duty to reduce emissions, and failed to engage in sustained communication about regional climate impacts in Australia. Beyond conceptual contributions, the findings hold important practical implications for research on the justice dimensions of climate policy. In particular, they highlight questions about how to mediate climate and alternative justice claims. An obvious first step is greater engagement with the multivalent and relational nature of climate justice vis-à-vis more established justice matrices. Allied to this is careful unpacking of the discourses and tactics used to promote both climate and alternative justice claims, to understand--and where necessary challenge--the processes through which different justice claims gain recognition (Bulkeley, Edwards and Fuller 2014). A second priority is further examination of how the justice arguments favoring climate action might be spatialized more effectively. Evidence from Australia suggests that framings of climate change as a long-term, international issue often fail to persuade key audiences compared with more localized and economically-focused narratives. One more spatially nuanced framing gaining momentum in Australia highlights energy justice as a way of 34 connecting global climate concerns to multi-scalar concerns about the financial, environmental, and health implications of energy production. Pearse (2015) describes how activists have shifted attention from carbon pricing towards new coal power projects in Victoria, Queensland, and Western Australia, using community campaigns to stress the protection of local landscapes and communities from blanket mining alongside broader climate themes. Parallel campaigns by Beyond Zero Emissions have involved nationwide tours promoting and large- and small-scale renewable-energy projects with local communities and decision-makers aimed at achieving 100 percent renewable energy across the electricity grid (Pearse 2015). Other spatially-focused justice narratives might target geographically-specific climate-related threats, for instance to water availability for agricultural communities in Australia’s Murray-Darling Basin, or widely-publicized threats to the Great Barrier Reef from the expansion of the Abbot Point deepwater port for coal exports (Bettini 2013). A further option is more spatialized portrayals of the justice co- benefits of climate action, such as improved health and transportation systems, to connect them compellingly to specific places and personal priorities (Chapman 2015). These are just a few options for giving climate justice greater geographical rootedness in climate policy, but there are doubtless many others. Either way, deeper embedding of climate justice into political decision-making remains a critical challenge, and further exploration of the multivalence and socio-spatial dimensions of justice claim-making remains an important frontier for research on climate justice. 35 Notes 1 However, Skitka, Winquist and Hutchinson (2003) argue that if a group is convinced that outcomes are moral or immoral, procedural fairness may be less important than outcomes due to the strength of a priori convictions. 2 The main obstacle to negotiations was that the Greens regarded the government’s target to reduce emissions to 5 percent below 2000 levels by 2020 as under-ambitious. Raising the target was problematic, however, because it was supported by the Coalition and industry. A compromise was reached whereby the Greens supported an initial fixed price of $23 to create incentives for emissions reduction in return for agreement that Australia’s emissions targets would be reviewed by the independent Climate Change Authority. 3 Formed by Clive Palmer, in 2013 with an agenda to repeal the CPM and restore Australia’s economic prosperity. 4 Economics is, of course, a form of ethical argumentation with its own normative compasses for deciding justifiable courses of action. However, the distinction Christoff draws is between: (i) ethical discourses centered on climate ethics and the normative appropriateness of different mitigation and adaptation solutions; and (ii) economic discourses about efficiency, welfare, development, and modernization, ranging from older economic discourses supporting resource-centered growth that entail weak valuations of nature and higher future discounting and bias cost-benefit calculations towards short-term economic security, employment, investment and welfare, to newer economic discourses that incorporate the future costs of climate change. Christoff’s ethical and economic discourses thus both contain normative standpoints but contest what matters when judging 36 the justice of different approaches to cost-sharing the burdens of climate impacts, mitigation and adaptation. I am grateful to one anonymous referee for this point. 5 Australia’s emissions are estimated to be 1.4 percent of the global total, but this figure excludes emissions from coal exports because these are attributed to countries where greenhouse gases are emitted for energy generation under Kyoto accounting rules. 6 As Peet and Harrison (2012) note, the term tax often invokes negative feelings among voters, while even revenue-neutral taxes is contentious either because voters disbelieve that environmental taxes can accomplish anything without imposing penalties. 37 References Abbott, T. 2009. Battlelines. Carlton, VIC: Melbourne University Press. ACIL Tasman. 2011. Impact of carbon price on black coal mining: Updated analysis of alternative carbon price scenarios. Brisbane: ACIL Tasman, https://www.qrc.org.au/_dbase_upl/ACIL%20Tasman%20report%202,%2030.9.11.pdf (last accessed 12 December 2014]. Australian Broadcasting Corporation. 2006. John Howard interview: Energy. http://www.abc.net.au/4corners/content/2006/s1738726.htm (last accessed 20 May 2015). Australian Conservative. 2011. Carbon tax to hit regional Australia the hardest. http://australianconservative.com/2011/08/carbon-tax-to-hit-regional-australia-the- hardest/ (last accessed 20 May 2015). Australian Government. 2011. Securing a clean energy future: The Australian Government's climate change plan. Commonwealth of Australia: Canberra. Australian Industry Group. 2013. Ai Group survey: Business pricing responses to Australia’s carbon tax, the first six months. http://www.aigroup.com.au/portal/binary/com.epicentric.contentmanagement.servlet.Con tentDeliveryServlet/LIVE_CONTENT/Publications/Reports/2013/Economics/Carbon_price_i mpacts_Jan_2013.pdf (last accessed 2 October 2015). Bacon, W. and C. Nash. 2012. Playing the media game. Journalism Studies 13 (2): 243–58. https://www.qrc.org.au/_dbase_upl/ACIL%20Tasman%20report%202,%2030.9.11.pdf http://www.abc.net.au/4corners/content/2006/s1738726.htm http://australianconservative.com/2011/08/carbon-tax-to-hit-regional-australia-the-hardest/ http://australianconservative.com/2011/08/carbon-tax-to-hit-regional-australia-the-hardest/ http://www.aigroup.com.au/portal/binary/com.epicentric.contentmanagement.servlet.ContentDeliveryServlet/LIVE_CONTENT/Publications/Reports/2013/Economics/Carbon_price_impacts_Jan_2013.pdf http://www.aigroup.com.au/portal/binary/com.epicentric.contentmanagement.servlet.ContentDeliveryServlet/LIVE_CONTENT/Publications/Reports/2013/Economics/Carbon_price_impacts_Jan_2013.pdf http://www.aigroup.com.au/portal/binary/com.epicentric.contentmanagement.servlet.ContentDeliveryServlet/LIVE_CONTENT/Publications/Reports/2013/Economics/Carbon_price_impacts_Jan_2013.pdf 38 Bailey, I., I. MacGill, R. Passey and H. Compston. 2012. The fall (and rise) of carbon pricing in Australia: A political strategy analysis of the carbon pollution reduction scheme. Environmental Politics 21 (5): 691–711. Beckman, L. and E. Page. 2008. Perspectives on justice, democracy and global climate change. Environmental Politics 17 (4): 527–35. Behm, A. 2015, No Minister: So you want to be a chief of staff? Melbourne: Melbourne University Press. Botterill, L. 2006. Soap operas, cenotaphs and sacred cows: countrymindedness and rural policy debate. Public Policy 1 (1): 23–36. Boykoff, M. 2008. The cultural politics of climate change discourse in UK tabloids. Political Geography 27 (5): 549–69. Büchs, M., N. Bardsley and S. Duwe. 2011. Who bears the brunt? Distributional effects of climate change mitigation policies. Critical Social Policy 31 (2): 285–307. Bulkeley, H. and P. Newell. 2010. Governing climate change. Abingdon: Routledge. Bulkeley, H., J. Carmin, V. Castán Broto, G. Edwards and S. Fuller. 2013. Climate justice and global cities: Mapping the emerging discourses. Global Environmental Change 23 (5): 914– 25. Bulkeley, H., G. Edwards and S. Fuller. 2014. Contesting climate justice in the city: Examining politics and practice in urban climate change experiments. Global Environmental Change 25: 31-40. 39 Burgmann, V. and H. A. Baer. 2012. Climate politics and the climate movement in Australia. Melbourne: Melbourne University Press. Caripis, L., J. Peel, L. Godden and R. Keenan. 2011. Australia's carbon pricing mechanism. Climate Law 2 (4): 583–603. Chapman, R. 2015. Time of useful consciousness: acting urgently on climate change. Wellington: Bridget Williams Books. Christoff, P. 2013. Climate discourse complexes, national climate regimes and Australian climate policy. Australian Journal of Politics and History 59 (3): 349–67. Cleugh, H., M. Stafford Smith, M. Battaglia and P. Graham. 2011. Climate change. Collongwood, VIA: CSIRO Publishing. Climate Institute. 2011. Jobs growth in a low pollution economy. http://www.climateinstitute.org.au/verve/_resources/tci_joblosses_mythbuster_august201 1.pdf (last accessed 12 December 2014). Cowell, R., G. Bristow and M. Munday. 2011. Acceptance, acceptability and environmental justice: The role of community benefits in wind energy development. Journal of Environmental Planning and Management 54 (4): 539–57. Crowley, K. 2007. Is Australia faking it? The Kyoto Protocol and the greenhouse policy challenge. Global Environmental Politics 7 (4): 118–39. ———. 2013. Pricing carbon: The politics of climate policy in Australia. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Climate Change 4 (6): 603–13. http://www.climateinstitute.org.au/verve/_resources/tci_joblosses_mythbuster_august2011.pdf http://www.climateinstitute.org.au/verve/_resources/tci_joblosses_mythbuster_august2011.pdf 40 DiFrancesco, D. A. and N. Young. 2011. Seeing climate change: The visual construction of global warming in Canadian national print media. Cultural Geographies 18 (4): 517–36. Dryzek, J. 2013. The Politics of the Earth: Environmental discourses (third edition). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Evans, T. 2006. Compulsory voting in Australia. Australian Electoral Commission. http://emailfooter.aec.gov.au/About_AEC/Publications/voting/files/compulsory-voting.pdf (last accessed 26 May 2015). Fiske, A. P. and P. Tetlock. 1997. Taboo trade-offs: Reactions to transactions that transgress the spheres of justice. Political Psychology 18 (2): 255–97. Flowerdew, R. and Martin, D. 2005. Methods in Human Geography: A Guide for Students doing a Research Project. Abingdon: Routledge. Fowler, A. 2013. Electoral and policy consequences of voter turnout: Evidence from compulsory voting in Australia. Quarterly Journal of Political Science 8 (2): 159–82. Fraser, N. 2001. Recognition with ethics? Theory, Culture and Society 18 (2-3): 21–42. Gardiner, S.M. 2006. A perfect moral storm: climate change, intergenerational ethics and the problem of moral corruption. Environmental Values 15 (3): 397–413. ———. 2011. A Perfect Moral Storm: The ethical tragedy of climate change. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Garnaut, R. 2008. The Garnaut Climate Change Review: Final report. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. http://emailfooter.aec.gov.au/About_AEC/Publications/voting/files/compulsory-voting.pdf 41 Garnaut, R. 2011. The Garnaut Review 2011: Australia in the global response to climate change. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Gavin, N. 2009. Addressing climate change: A media perspective. Environmental Politics 18 (5): 765–80. Grasso, M. 2010. An ethical approach to climate adaptation finance. Global Environmental Change 20 (1): 74–81. Gratton, M. and M. Wroe. 2011. Abbott's blood oath to repeal carbon tax. Sydney Morning Herald 13 October 2011 http://www.smh.com.au/national/abbotts-blood-oath-to-repeal- carbon-tax-20111012-1ll80.html (last accessed 3 June 2014). Greer, A. 2014. Towards climate justice? A critical reflection on legal subjectivity and climate injustice: Warning signals, patterned hierarchies, directions for future law and policy. Journal of Human Rights and the Environment 5 (0): 103–33. Gross, C. 2007. Community perspectives of wind energy in Australia: The application of a justice and community fairness framework to increase social acceptance. Energy Policy 35 (5): 2727–36. Giljum, S. and N. Eisenmenger. 2004. North-south trade and the distribution of environmental goods and burdens. A biophysical perspective. Journal of Environment and Development 13 (1): 73–100. Hafer, C. and J. Olson. 2003. An analysis of empirical research on the scope of justice. Personality and Social Psychology Review 7 (4): 311–23. http://www.smh.com.au/national/abbotts-blood-oath-to-repeal-carbon-tax-20111012-1ll80.html http://www.smh.com.au/national/abbotts-blood-oath-to-repeal-carbon-tax-20111012-1ll80.html 42 Heyward, M. 2007. Equity and international climate change negotiations: a matter of perspective. Climate Policy 7 (6): 518–34. Harrison, K. and L. M. Sundstrom. 2010. Conclusion: The comparative politics of climate change. In Global commons, domestic decisions: The comparative politics of climate change, eds K. Harrison and L. M. Sundstrom, 261–90. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Hillman, M. 2006. Situated justice in environmental decision-making: Lessons from river management in Southeastern Australia. Geoforum 37 (5): 695–707. Hornborg, A. 1998. Towards an ecological theory of unequal exchange: articulating world system theory and ecological economics. Ecological Economics 25 (1): 127-136. Howarth, D. 2009. Power, discourse and policy: Articulating a hegemonic approach to critical policy studies. Critical Policy Studies 3 (3-4): 309–35. Hsieh, H.F. and Shannon, S.E. 2005. Three approaches to qualitative content analysis. Qualitative Health Research 15 (9): 1277–88. Klinsky, S. 2015. Justice and boundary setting in greenhouse gas cap and trade policy: A case study of the Western Climate Initiative. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 105 (1): 105-22. Klinsky, S. and H. Dowlatabadi. 2009. Conceptualizations of justice in climate policy. Climate Policy 9 (1): 88-108. Klinsky, S., H. Dowlatabadi and T. McDaniels. 2012. Comparing public rationales for justice trade-offs in mitigation and adaptation climate policy dilemmas. Global Environmental Change 22 (4): 862–76. 43 Kuehn, R. 2000. A taxonomy of environmental justice. Environmental Law Reporter 30 (9): 10681–703. Kurz, T., M. Augoustinos and S. Crabb. 2010. Contesting the ‘national interest’ and maintaining ‘our lifestyle’: A discursive analysis of political rhetoric around climate change. British Journal of Social Psychology 49 (3): 601–25. Lawrence, P. 2009. Australian climate policy and the Asia Pacific Partnership on Clean Development and Climate (APP). From Howard to Rudd: Continuity or change? International Environmental Agreements 9 (3): 281–99. Lind, A. and T. Tyler. 1988. The social psychology of procedural justice. New York: Plenum Press. MacCoun, R. 2005. Voice, control and belonging: The double-edged sword of procedural fairness. Annual Review of Law and Social Science 1 (1): 171–201. Meng, S., M. Siriwardana and J. McNeill. 2013. The environmental and economic impact of the carbon tax in Australia. Environmental and Resource Economics 54 (3): 313–32. Meyer, L. and D. Roser. 2010. Climate justice and historical emissions. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 13 (1): 229–53. Okereke, C. 2010. Climate justice and the international regime. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Climate Change 1 (3): 462–74. Page, E. 2008. Distributing the burdens of climate change. Environmental Politics 17 (4): 556–75. 44 Palmer United Party. 2013. National Policy. http://palmerunited.com/wp- content/uploads/2013/07/Palmer-United-Party-National-Policy-16MAY2013.pdf (last accessed 20 May 2015). Parks, B. and J. T. Roberts. 2008. Inequality and the global climate regime: Breaking the north-south impasse. Cambridge Review of International Affairs 21 (4): 621–48. Pearse, G. 2009. Quarry vision: coal, climate change and the end of the resources boom. Quarterly Essay 33: 1–140. Pearse, R. 2015. The political economy of carbon pricing in Australia: Contestation, the state and governance failure. Unpublished PhD thesis, University of New South Wales. Peet, C. and Harrison, K. 2012. Historical legacies and policy reform: Diverse regional reactions to British Columbia’s carbon tax. BC Studies 173 (Spring 2012): 97–122. Pietsch, J. and McAllister, I. 2010. ‘A diabolical challenge’: Public opinion and climate change policy in Australia. Environmental Politics 19 (2): 217–36. Pralle, S. 2009. Agenda-setting and climate change. Environmental Politics 18 (5): 781–99. Productivity Commission. 2011. Carbon emission policies in key economies. Melbourne: Productivity Commission. http://www.pc.gov.au/__data/assets/pdf_file/0003/109830/carbon-prices.pdf (last accessed 1 October 2015). Rawls, J. 1972. A theory of justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press. http://palmerunited.com/wp-content/uploads/2013/07/Palmer-United-Party-National-Policy-16MAY2013.pdf http://palmerunited.com/wp-content/uploads/2013/07/Palmer-United-Party-National-Policy-16MAY2013.pdf http://www.pc.gov.au/__data/assets/pdf_file/0003/109830/carbon-prices.pdf 45 Roberts, T. and B.C. Parks. 2009. Ecologically unequal exchange, ecological debt, and climate justice: the history and implications of three related ideas for a new social movement. International Journal of Comparative Sociology 50 (3-4): 385–409. Rootes, C. 2011. Denied, deferred, triumphant? Climate change, carbon trading and the Greens in the Australian federal election of 21 August 2010. Environmental Politics 20 (3): 410–17. ———. 2014. A referendum on the carbon tax? The 2013 Australian election, the Greens, and the environment. Environmental Politics 23 (1): 166–73. Routledge, P. 2011. Translocal climate justice solidarities. In The Oxford handbook of climate change and society, ed. J. Dryzek, R. Norgaard and D. Schlosberg, 384–98. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Rudd, K. 2008. Building a better world together: Speech at Kyoto University 9 June 2008. http://pmtranscripts.dpmc.gov.au/release/transcript-15955 (last accessed 2 October 2015). Schlosberg, D. 2004. Reconceiving environmental justice: Global movements and political theories. Environmental Politics 13 (3): 517–40. ———. 2012. Climate justice and capabilities: A framework for adaptation policy. Ethics and International Affairs 26 (4): 445–61. Shue, H. 1993. Subsistence emissions and luxury emissions. Law and Policy 15 (1): 39–59. ———. 1999. Global environment and international inequality. International Affairs 75 (3): 531–45. http://pmtranscripts.dpmc.gov.au/release/transcript-15955 46 Singer, P. 2002. One world: the ethics of globalization. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Speck, D. 2010. A hot topic? Climate change mitigation policies, politics, and the media in Australia. Human Ecology Review 17 (2): 125–34. Skitka, L., J. Winquist and S. Hutchinson. 2003. Are outcome fairness and outcome favourability distinguishable psychological constructs? A meta-analytic review. Social Justice Research 16 (4): 309–41. The Age. 2003. I won't ratify Kyoto Protocol: PM. 2 December 2003, http://www.theage.com.au/articles/2003/12/02/1070127416251.html (last accessed 5 December 2014). The Australian. 2011. Carbon tax ‘will cost 4000 coal jobs’. http://www.theaustralian.com.au/national-affairs/carbon-tax-will-cost-4000-coal- jobs/story-fn59niix-1226074538742 (last accessed 12 December 2014). The Guardian. 2013a. Missing logic of Australian prime minister's denial of climate change link to bushfires. http://www.theguardian.com/environment/planet- oz/2013/oct/29/climate-change-bushfires-smoking-denial-tony-abbott (last accessed 12 December 2014). The Guardian. 2013b. Campaign watch: 2013 Australian election interactive map. http://www.theguardian.com/world/datablog/interactive/2013/aug/19/australian-election- campaign-map (last accessed 12 December 2014). Vanderheiden, S. 2008. Atmospheric justice: A political theory of climate change. Oxford: Oxford University Press. http://www.theage.com.au/articles/2003/12/02/1070127416251.html http://www.theaustralian.com.au/national-affairs/carbon-tax-will-cost-4000-coal-jobs/story-fn59niix-1226074538742 http://www.theaustralian.com.au/national-affairs/carbon-tax-will-cost-4000-coal-jobs/story-fn59niix-1226074538742 http://www.theguardian.com/environment/planet-oz/2013/oct/29/climate-change-bushfires-smoking-denial-tony-abbott http://www.theguardian.com/environment/planet-oz/2013/oct/29/climate-change-bushfires-smoking-denial-tony-abbott http://www.theguardian.com/world/datablog/interactive/2013/aug/19/australian-election-campaign-map http://www.theguardian.com/world/datablog/interactive/2013/aug/19/australian-election-campaign-map 47 Walker, G. 2009. Beyond distribution and proximity: Exploring the multiple spatialities of environmental justice. Antipode 41 (4): 614–36. Walker, G. and H. Bulkeley. 2006. Geographies of environmental justice. Geoforum 37 (5): 655–659. Walker, G. and R. Day. 2012. Fuel poverty as injustice: Integrating distribution, recognition and procedure in the struggle for affordable warmth. Energy Policy 49: 69–75. Walker, G. and E. Shove. 2007. Ambivalence, sustainability and the governance of socio- technical transitions. Journal of Environmental Policy and Planning 9 (3): 213–25. IAN BAILEY is Professor in the School of Geography, Earth and Environmental Sciences at Plymouth University, Plymouth, UK. E-mail: ian.bailey@plymouth.ac.uk. His research interests include climate and energy politics and the social dimensions of sustainability. 48 work_7obswvpptvaj5f4jlitzgggn6u ---- 086730_TRE_47-70.qxd [ 4 7 ] TRE. . Theory and Research in Education Copyright © 2008, sage publications, www.sagepublications.com vol 6(1) 47–70 ISSN 1477-8785 DOI: 10.1177/1477878507086730 Educational justice and the gifted m i c h a e l s . m e r r y Beloit College,Wisconsin, USA a b s t r a c t This article examines two basic questions: first, what constitutes a gifted person, and secondly, is there justification in making special educational provision for gifted children, where special provision involves spending more on their education than on the education of ‘normal’ children? I consider a hypothetical case for allocating extra resources for the gifted, and argue that gifted children are generally denied educational justice if they fail to receive an education that adequately challenges them. I further argue that an adequately challenging education is essential to human flourishing, but that most children can be adequately challenged in schools in ways that promote flourishing without doing so at the expense of other children. k e y w o r d s adequate challenge, fair equality of opportunity, flourishing, giftedness W i t h t h e p a s s a g e o f the Elementary and Secondary Education Act (ESEA) in 1965, the needs of various minority children in the United States became the subject of federal policy.Title I legislation aimed to close the achieve- ment gap between high and low achieving children,‘especially the achievement gaps between the minority and non-minority students, and between disadvan- taged children and their more advantaged peers’ (ESEA, Sec. 1001.3). Some years later, the Rehabilitation Act (1973) and the Education for All Handicapped Children Act (PL 94–142, 1975) were passed to provide educational opportu- nities for children with disabilities and special needs.This legislation effectively required the inclusion – to one degree or another into regular classroom instruction – of children with special needs whose parents wished to avail themselves of the public schools. Assessment and accountability procedures were also prescribed.1 Eventually this legislation would be ratified as the Individuals with Disabilities Education Act (IDEA).As an entitlement program, schools receiving federal funds under IDEA are responsible for actively seeking out children who may benefit from the services that said legislation addresses. 086730_TRE_47-70.qxd 2/26/08 10:23 AM Page 47 The relevance of these developments is to highlight an important backdrop to the demand for equitable education for children whose parents consider them to be ‘gifted’. In the last 30 years or so, a growing number of mostly white, middle-class parents have expressed outrage at the failure of public schools to adequately challenge their children. Gifted children, the argument runs, are underserved, are being ‘held back’, and are being asked to pull others up without being challenged themselves. Anecdote after anecdote is served up suggesting that gifted children suffer ennui, frustration and often disaffec- tion with their schooling as a result of not being sufficiently challenged. Some parents also complain that they are forced to pay for private education or tutoring in order to challenge their children with exceptional abilities or talents. Many of these parents have demanded that states and/or the federal government appropriate funds for separate gifted and talented programming as a matter of equity and equal opportunity. However, despite vociferous demands for special accommodation and programming, special provisions for so-called gifted children have largely fallen on deaf ears.2 Individual states may address the matter separately,3 and in certain instances court decisions have required that some programs for gifted children be provided.Vexed that more than 140 per cent extra is spent on special education services than on ‘enrichment’ services for quick learners, a small but committed core of parents continue to push for special legislation and funding for Talented and Gifted programming (Cloud, 2007; Davidson and Davidson, 2004).4 Vocal critics argue that giftedness labeling and programming in public schools is elitist and operates according to doubtful psychometric assessment tools which generally privilege a select few at the expense of the majority. Making the debate possibly more contentious is the belief many have that the number of truly exceptional children who are likely to require extraordinary educational provision is rather small – unlike the population of children deemed to have ‘special needs’.5 Yet I argue that, while only a small number of truly exceptional children are likely to require extraordinary educational provision, to not adequately challenge these children, who hail from all ethnic groups and social classes, is unequivocally to fail them. This article addresses two important questions. 1. What constitutes a gifted person? 2. Are we justified in making special educational provision for gifted children, where special provision involves spending more on their education than on the education of ‘normal’ children? Taking the first item, I will attempt to define the notion of giftedness, noting its inherent complexity and contested nature. I will briefly consider a multi- factorial concept of intelligence and suggest that notwithstanding its advantages Theory and Research in Education 6(1) [ 4 8 ] 086730_TRE_47-70.qxd 2/26/08 10:23 AM Page 48 it cannot supply a theoretical foundation for gifted education and may actually serve to undermine it.This is because intelligence or ability too broadly defined renders gifted education either trivial or useless.Though advocates of ‘multiple intelligence’ will locate giftedness in various domains (e.g. intuitive, intraper- sonal, affective), I will concern myself with its cognitive aspects in this article. As a corollary to the first question, I will then examine the difficulties in deter- mining who is gifted, noting cultural, environmental and institutional barriers. Then, taking the second question, I will consider a hypothetical case for allocating extra resources for the gifted, considering various political and educa- tional arguments. I will turn my attention to Rawls’ second axiom of justice, focusing in particular on Fair Equality of Opportunity (FEO), which requires not only ‘that public offices and social positions be open in the formal sense, but that all should have a fair chance to attain them’ (Rawls, 2001: 43). That is, persons with similar native endowments (talent and ability), and the initiative or motivation to put those talents to effective use, ought to have more or less the same opportunities to do so irrespective of their family and social class origins. Notwithstanding its philosophical appeal, I will show that FEO can not justify differential educational provision for those who have more talent than others. Leaving Rawls aside, then, I will introduce a principle of adequate educational challenge.Thus, in response to my second question, my central claim is this: All children, including the gifted, deserve to be adequately challenged as a matter of fairness, even though the specification of what is adequate will continue to be somewhat elusive. I argue that gifted children are generally denied educational justice if they fail to receive an education that adequately challenges them. I also argue that an adequately challenging education is essential to human flourishing. I will further argue that most children can be adequately challenged in schools in ways that promote flourishing without doing so at the expense of other children. Justice demands that classroom instruction – and educational opportunities generally – should not be arranged in such a way as to unduly advantage children whose abilities arguably surpass those of their classmates. Rather, educational opportunities must be structured so as to benefit all learners irrespective of socio-economic background, parental and teacher recom- mendation, or test scores. w h at c o n s t i t u t e s a g i f t e d p e r s o n ? Giftedness is one of those terms that would seem to defy precise description. Yet how we conceive of giftedness is hugely significant because this will inform not only our understanding of who gifted learners are, but moreover Merry: Educational justice and the gifted [ 4 9 ] 086730_TRE_47-70.qxd 2/26/08 10:23 AM Page 49 how we ought to design and foster educational opportunities. Experts use a number of criteria when discussing gifted individuals.These criteria include a tendency to ask probing questions, signs of astute analysis, or the ability to synthesize complex information (Heller et al., 2005). Others speak of being goal- driven, possessing greater metacognition, a faster pace of learning, greater flexibility in problem-solving skills, and a penchant for complexity and challenge (Callahan and Miller, 2005). Other factors are also germane, such as intrinsic motivation and sustained attention or task commitment, but it remains unclear just how other these are to be factored in. Matters become increasingly complex when we include learning styles, creativity, memory capacity, strategies for coping with stress, and good old-fashioned practice and hard work.What is clear is that a lot of information is needed to properly evaluate what a child’s abilities or gifts are and how they might best be cultivated.Yet given the fact that ‘giftedness may be elusive in its manner and context of manifestation’ (VanTassel-Baska, 2005a: 364), some have suggested that we broaden the possibilities for identifying unusually talented individuals. One way to do that is to consider a multifactorial concept of intelligence. A multifactorial concept of intelligence takes a more expansive view of things, effectively abrogating the popular notion that only a few individuals possess unique talents or unusually high ability. On such an understanding, all but the most incapacitated and irresolute possess (and possibly excel at) one or more types of intelligence and are capable of cultivating other intelligences over time that have been undernourished or in which, for the time being, they are lacking in proficiency. Thus individuals with developed spatial or interpersonal intel- ligences are not as likely to demonstrate mathematical or analytical aptitude.Yet where competency may be lacking in one form of intelligence, its advocates answer that this can be corrected by providing adequate learning opportunities and an appropriate level of challenge. According to Howard Gardner: [T]he ‘smarter’ the environment and the more powerful the interventions and the avail- able resources, the more proficient people will become, and the less important will be their particular genetic inheritance. (Gardner, 1999: 88) On this understanding ‘giftedness’ appears not to be a state of being for most children; it is something more akin to a process. Thus, given the right set of conditions and opportunities, many more children than at present would certainly be considered ‘gifted’; indeed, most children might be ‘gifted’ in at least one area. In fact this is the direction in which such theories can be extrapolated.Yet the problem with appropriating a multifactorial formulation of intelligence is that by expanding the definition of giftedness or ability to encompass all but the most incorrigibly untalented and mentally challenged, the notion of ‘gifted- ness’ becomes rather devoid of content.6 Indeed, for giftedness to apply in some broad sense to all children except the most severely disabled is to dilute Theory and Research in Education 6(1) [ 5 0 ] 086730_TRE_47-70.qxd 2/26/08 10:23 AM Page 50 the significance of giftedness that its advocates insist make it remarkable in the first place. Further, while it is desirable that schools expand the notion of gift- edness to include those whose abilities and talents fall outside the time-honored categories of math, science and language arts, it does not follow that the gifted in these or any other subject or activity are deserving of special or separate instruction. Rather, it throws down a challenge to provide good teaching and effective instruction to all children irrespective of how well they perform on evaluative instruments whose purpose is to assess abilities according to a set of criteria on which there is little agreement. So the problem of achieving consensus on the precise meaning of gifted- ness continues to dog the field, and the difficulties are compounded by those who interchange terms like ‘genius’ or ‘prodigy’ with ‘gifted’ (Davidson and Davidson, 2004). In light of these difficulties, some argue that we ought to do away with the gifted label altogether: [Defining] giftedness is a matter of values and policy, not empirical research.And in many, if not most, states, definitions are not mandated.The result is that local educators are free, indeed required, to choose, or write, a definition of giftedness for their program for gifted students, one that, to a large extent, determines who will and who will not be gifted. In other words, giftedness in the schools is something we confer, not something we discover. It is a matter of educational policy, not a matter of scientific diagnosis. It is a social con- struction, not a fact of nature. (Borland, 2005: 8) Others, however, continue to employ definitions – albeit with great caution – even as they admit that the entire enterprise is ‘nebulous and fraught with difficulty. The highly able child is someone who has significantly greater aptitude for some aspect of intellectual learning than would be considered typical for their age and background. (Winstanley, 2003: 35) Now, clearly this broad definition does little to allay the vagueness problem, and, given the difficulties in arriving at a definition on which all can agree, I shall simply note here the contentiousness of the terminology in question.Yet, while the difficulty in defining the gifted child can be messy business, prac- tical demands require that we use some definition to refer to those children whose unusual aptitude sets them apart from their peers. Throughout I will use ‘gifted’ to refer to children with unusual abilities. ‘Unusual abilities’ on its own is terribly imprecise, of course, and unhelpful without further qualification. For example, a great many individuals possess some unusual talent or ability that few others do. Most of these ‘talents’ are physical eccentricities – often showcased on late-night television – and are generally quite useless aside from their (limited) amusement value. So possessing unusual abilities may mean little more than having atypical characteristics or abilities, and there is nothing noteworthy in the gifted sense about this. Merry: Educational justice and the gifted [ 5 1 ] 086730_TRE_47-70.qxd 2/26/08 10:23 AM Page 51 Further, not all gifted children are recognized as such, and this may prevent them from being correctly identified in the first place. Indeed, some may demonstrate decidedly anti-social behavior and unremarkable test results. In other cases, however, children possess abilities simply not valued in the culture or society they inhabit. Either way, only appropriately varied diagnostics and monitoring can determine whether a child is simply ‘quirky’ or exceptional. Though some will doubtless prefer that we appreciate the various ways in which giftedness manifests itself (e.g. intuitively, affectively), by unusual abil- ities I have in mind those who possess extraordinary cognitive capacities well beyond what is considered ‘average’ for one’s age or background. Thus, like Winstanley, I will limit my use of giftedness here to its cognitive sense. w h o a r e t h e g i f t e d ? The common understanding of giftedness among its advocates assumes that gifted children have, innately, some learning capacity (parsed out in a variety of forms) that other children do not. Yet, aside from the conceptual diffi- culties, there are also a number of empirical realities that create difficulties for identifying gifted persons. First, some cultures will discourage any form of recognition of individual talent, preferring instead to emphasize communal values and group efforts. Second, children with unusual abilities often have their talents and intelligence obscured by several factors.There may be learning disabilities of various kinds (e.g. dyslexia) or sensory impairment (e.g. hearing loss). Some gifted children may also suffer from various chemical imbalances (e.g. hyperactive thyroid) or dwell in unstable home environments, thus affecting their academic performance. Further, a child’s elder siblings may not have been model students, thus leading many teachers to expect less of them. Other criticisms point to the fact that tests used to measure intelligence are able to tell us little about how the mind works or what a child’s aptitude or learning potential actually is. Individuals who score well on tests may be highly intelligent or they may simply be proficient at taking tests. Finally, because of the ways that tracking and ability grouping in public schools actually work, ‘gifted’ labeling frequently maps along both racial and social class lines.Whites and Asians are twice as likely as Latinos or African Americans to be labeled ‘gifted’ even with comparable test scores (Borland and Wright, 1994; Ford and Harris, 1999; Gordon and Birdglall, 2005; Moore et al., 2005). There may be a variety of reasons for this, including the learning opportunities that some parents provide their children at home or outside of the home/school. Be that as it may, parents and teachers routinely make certain assumptions about children – particularly of a certain social class background – and their putative abilities.What is more, these assumptions quickly become labels, and these labels usually stick. Theory and Research in Education 6(1) [ 5 2 ] 086730_TRE_47-70.qxd 2/26/08 10:23 AM Page 52 Laura Purdy writes that not only are there problems with identifying appropriate participants in special programs, there is the problem of ‘snobbery among the chosen, together with the lack of self-confidence among those not chosen [and] such labels may be artificial and self-fulfilling prophecies based on inadequate criteria’ (2007: 318). In light of this worrying trend, there are good reasons to question whether most children who are designated ‘gifted learners’ in schools are truly deserving of the label. (Similarly, our skepticism is justified as it concerns the assignment of ‘learning disabilities’ to children from various minority groups (Harry and Klingner , 2006; Losen and Orfield, 2002).) The manner in which social class bears upon gifted labeling is particularly telling. Consider the social conditions that facilitate the cultivation of talents and the level of interest and effort that are likely to accrue given (a) the right learning conditions to foster those talents including appropriate role models and expectations; and (b) a set of opportunities and incentives that value and reward certain talents. Take, for example, a child whose latent proficiency lies in composing music, yet she has non-musical parents and attends a school that has no budget for a music program. Were she to have musically talented parents or were this music program to exist, she might have the conditions under which her untapped talents might flourish. Moreover, if she is lucky enough to have her hidden talents recognized and valued by her parents and teachers, she would have at her disposal a strong incentive to continue developing her talents in ways that open doors of opportunity not available to her in the absence of such parents or programs. The issue here is certainly whether or not a child’s talents and/or gifts are recognized and valued, but also whether the opportunities and conditions exist for those uncultivated talents and gifts to emerge and to blossom in the first place. Of course opportunities and incentives are no guarantee of interest, inten- tion or effort; nor are opportunities a substitute for actual aptitude or talent. And while cultivating talent entails more than merely finding out what one is good at, opportunities continue to correspond closely to social class and the sorts of preferences and tastes social class affords.Thus a privileged child lacking in the dexterity or motivation required for, say, gymnastics may adapt her preferences, provided she has both the requisite guidance and resources, and pursue other, culturally valued, pursuits. Even in the absence of motivation or talent, a socially privileged child may turn her attention to other activities which may or may not satisfy culturally established criteria for valued pursuits. Moreover, given the range of choices available to a socially privileged child, the likelihood that she will experience personal satisfaction and possibly even material success resulting from her pursuits remains quite high. Now of course social class will mean different things in different contexts and the level of well-being one experiences will vary greatly depending on a variety Merry: Educational justice and the gifted [ 5 3 ] 086730_TRE_47-70.qxd 2/26/08 10:23 AM Page 53 of things, including the availability and/or quality of education, communal life, housing, nourishment, medical care, etc. at one’s disposal. (By well-being I mean an individual’s capacity to engage in intrinsically worthwhile activities, where these are not entirely determined by individual preferences.)7Yet in industrialized societies, which are where discussions of giftedness routinely take place, middle- class parents are far more likely to have comparable educational attainment, to share similar educational aspirations for their children, and to have the means for procuring them. For socially privileged persons these conditions are highly conducive to interaction with others similarly educated and well-informed. Research shows that peer effects on learning can be as significant as the quality of instruction a child receives (Swift, 2003). Children who socialize with others whose interests have been shaped and molded by well-educated parents are far more likely to adopt similar interests and to cultivate the skills necessary both for meaningful learning and material success. Why is this important? Its importance lies in the positional outcomes various educational opportunities bestow. Most poor parents also have high aspir- ations for their children but they are far more likely to have leveled aspirations owing to (a) their lower social-class standing that has undoubtedly resulted in part from access to inferior education; (b) the lack of material means that denies advantages more affluent parents take for granted; and (c) their encoun- ters with discriminatory behavior in the school, marketplace and society generally. Thus, socially privileged parents may avail themselves of structured daycare services, pre-schooling and extracurricular activities that are largely unavailable to those without comparable networking skills or disposable income. Research also shows that the amount and quality of adult–child inter- action is hugely different, on average, between social classes (Lareau, 2002; Ogbu, 2003; Rothstein, 2004). Opportunities to learn both inside and outside of the home only further that advantage. In short, in the absence of egalitarian intervention, the positional goods that increase the social capital (e.g. knowledge attainment, job readiness and satisfaction) for one group of children will unavoidably diminish the social capital of less advantaged children.8 Given the endless number of opportunities to cultivate abilities and talents that more privileged children typically enjoy, many educational philosophers and policy makers have argued that more ought to be done to challenge all children irrespective of who they are, whether through compensatory means such as Head Start, or simply with higher expectations, role modeling and nurture. Even so, the question of what schools ought to do for the gifted looms large. For all of the advantages that children of socially privileged parents enjoy – including greater access to gifted education programs, magnet and private schools – the fact remains that some children possess exceptional abilities regardless of the income bracket into which they were born. Theory and Research in Education 6(1) [ 5 4 ] 086730_TRE_47-70.qxd 2/26/08 10:23 AM Page 54 None of this settles the question of what the gifted need or deserve. The definitional quandary does not remove the need to address the learning needs of gifted children. If unchallenged in school, the gifted may simply disengage (as similarly happens with slower learners whose contributions are seldom valued) or languish from boredom, thus affecting their motivation to learn and their general academic performance. In what follows I will argue that a rather strong case can be made for channeling extra resources into the education of the gifted – thus increasing their learning opportunities – on the understanding that doing so is likely to benefit others. a h y p o t h e t i c a l a r g u m e n t f o r e x t r a p r o v i s i o n In a society eager to recruit the best and brightest engineers, doctors, researchers, architects and solicitors,9 the case for funding and providing a more rigorous curriculum for the most able seems especially strong. Indeed, to many it will seem obvious that societies work against their own best interests when, say, advances in science and medicine stall due to the unwillingness of govern- ment to invest in the talents of the gifted. Because we do not wish to needlessly squander the talents of the best and brightest, failing to cultivate the raw material of talent or intelligence such children embody constitutes a form of neglect. (I will return to this.) Once we accept that investing in the best talents is not only fair and good for those individuals but also likely accrues benefits (what economists refer to as ‘externalities’) to significant numbers of others besides, it remains for us only to identify who the gifted are and determine what specifically can be done to maximize the benefits. Where schools are concerned, learning opportunities need only be provided and arranged so as to foster outcomes that are good for the gifted and optimal for society. Consequently, ‘adequate challenge’ for some learners may require additional educational resources. But this is too quick. First of all, prima facie these arguments are conse- quentialist, and consequentialism will swiftly run into conflict with the requirements of educational justice. Educational justice requires that the State provide basic educational opportunities to all children irrespective of social- class background or ability, knowing that opportunities are normally contin- gent on the enabling effects education typically affords. One may call these instrumental benefits because education supplies individuals with the means to meet the various minimal demands that citizenship requires (including basic literacy and financial savvy) and also to enhance one’s sense of well- being. Thus, with a sufficient amount and quality of education one may take up meaningful vocational pursuits and forms of leisure as well as the relation- ships that derive from these. More broadly, education also supplies intrinsic Merry: Educational justice and the gifted [ 5 5 ] 086730_TRE_47-70.qxd 2/26/08 10:23 AM Page 55 benefits, which roughly translate as that which enhances human flourishing. Concerning what is just, Amy Gutmann observes that: A good case can be made for the use of education above the minimum to compensate less gifted and less motivated children for their undeserved disadvantages. Another good case can be made for using educational resources above the threshold to develop new skills and interests in all children, which might be useful to society as well as satisfying to citizens in the future. (Gutmann, 1999:135) Especially given that children with disabilities already struggle to keep up with their more able peers, learning opportunities that appear to favor the already advantaged require further justification. Some children will require more resources for the supplementary services necessary for even the possibility of attaining a normal life, and arguably this should take priority. Concerning how best to educate the gifted, I have hinted at a number of problems with a special provisions approach, not the least of which is that it promotes the sort of elitism and special treatment with which gifted program- ming (often in the form of ‘flexible’ or homogeneous grouping) has rightly or wrongly come to be identified. Further, given the way in which schools have often tended to reproduce social classes and respond to the demands of more privileged and educated parents, a special provisions approach, uncritically applied, will likely favor those whose abilities suggest social privilege rather than exceptional ability.10 Lastly, the manner in which separate instruction occurs tends to advance the interests of a few at the expense of those who are arguably just as capable of benefiting from more challenging instruction, including many underperforming gifted children. These responses can be answered, up to a point. First, I have little doubt that unreserved approval could be won for the allocation of extra resources to the education of the gifted if it could be shown that the additional resources would make ‘an appropriate contribution to the good of others by training and educating their native endowments and putting them to work [within] a fair system of social cooperation’ (Rawls, 2001: 68). In principle, policy makers could design incentives that encourage individuals with greater endowments or motivation to seize enhanced learning opportunities in such a way as to greatly benefit others, especially those less well off.11 Consider the way in which Rawls’ second axiom of justice speaks to this: Social and economic inequalities are to satisfy two conditions: first, they are to be attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair equality of oppor- tunity; and second, they are to be to the greatest benefit of the least-advantaged mem- bers of society. (Rawls, 2001: 42–3) (The first part of this axism,) Fair Equality of Opportunity (FEO) and (the second part of this axism,) Difference Principle (DP) should not be run together.12 Yet, allocations of additional resources to gifted students might in Theory and Research in Education 6(1) [ 5 6 ] 086730_TRE_47-70.qxd 2/26/08 10:23 AM Page 56 principle satisfy both parts of this axiom. FEO is satisfied because individuals with similar levels of talent and motivation are to be given the opportunities necessary to exploit their talents in competitions that determine who gets the best social positions.The DP is also satisfied, for it tolerates inequalities so long as over time the benefits to the least advantaged are as great as possible. The DP expresses the idea of reciprocity, and its intent is to regulate the tension between efficiency and (in)equality among free and equal citizens, so that ‘those who gain more are to do so on terms acceptable to those who gain less, and in particular to those who gain the least’ (Rawls, 2001: 123). Indeed, reasonable investments in the talents and abilities of some allow for what Rawls calls ‘mutually beneficial complementarities,’ which may – and, with the reciprocity constraint, ought to – enhance the quality of life of others possessing fewer talents. For example, persons with certain talents in medicine may contribute both to the field of medicine generally (comprising many specialties) as well as to the broader society in need of medical services. And it is not an injustice to permit some to excel in certain pursuits while leaving excellence in different pursuits to others. It is only an injustice when opportunities and their rewards are provided for some at the expense of others. Rawls further explains how reciprocity frames the moral responsibility of the more fortunate: [T]he better endowed (who have a more fortunate place in the distribution of native endowments they do not morally deserve) are encouraged to acquire still further bene- fits – they are already benefited by their fortunate place in that distribution – on condi- tion that they train their native endowments and use them in ways that contribute to the good of the less endowed (whose less fortunate place in the distribution they also do not morally deserve). Reciprocity is a moral idea situated between impartiality, which is altru- istic, on the one side and mutual advantage on the other. (Rawls, 2001: 76–7) So the DP supplies a reciprocal basis for aiding the highly abled, and its primary justification is to secure justice for those less abled. Put another way, higher compensation earned by the better endowed would be predicated on developing and using the talents in labor that will benefit the worst off. Indeed, higher compensation becomes the incentive to develop and use the talents of the more able in a specific way, and how the economy is shaped (e.g. through labor and taxation law) ought to ensure that higher compensation for the more talented benefits the worst off. (This is the thinking behind state incentives designed to pay the most experienced teachers higher salaries if they will agree to teach for an extended period in its most underperforming schools.) Reciprocity, on Rawls’ theory, is the basis for our responsibility to others in a system built on fair terms of cooperation. Others deserve consid- eration not on the basis of whether or not they possess certain abilities but rather because they share in common the moral qualities of being human. These qualities include physical and psychological integrity and a capacity for Merry: Educational justice and the gifted [ 5 7 ] 086730_TRE_47-70.qxd 2/26/08 10:23 AM Page 57 sympathy and mutual respect. A number of problems attend the DP vis-a-vis the disabled, which I shall not discuss here.13 While FEO and the DP thus appear to be a promising foundation for special educational provision for the gifted, insuperable difficulties remain. First, opportunities – such as special educational opportunities for the gifted – generally can not be justified on the basis of morally irrelevant factors, such as native endowments, i.e. those one does not morally deserve. So the gifted do not deserve special educational accommodations in the moral sense of being entitled to or having earned special treatment by virtue of their native endow- ments. Further, opportunities for the more able and talented are bound by the moral constraints of reciprocity, and failures of reciprocity in existing societies would undermine the apparent Rawlsian basis for special educational provision for the gifted. In existing societies, it is unclear how gifted education and rewards for the more talented would reliably lead to benefits for the less advan- taged. So while FEO and the DP go some distance in correcting the defects of formal equality of opportunity – careers open to talents – and do not prohibit properly structured differential provision, FEO nevertheless not only fails to supply us with the justification required for additional resources (if and when they are needed) in order to adequately challenge gifted children, it also fails in my view to support an argument for gifted education. DP may permit the investment of additional resources in the education of gifted students in some circumstances, but does not require it. In the circumstances of justice in which it would be permitted, the consequentialist considerations noted above might recommend it, but in the unjust circumstances of existing societies those consequentialist considerations would not be sufficient to overcome the prima facie injustice of favoring those already favored in the lottery of talents. w h at a r e t h e g i f t e d o w e d ? The question before us invites both empirical and philosophical responses. Empirically, owing to a number of contingencies that will need to be worked out in specific school districts, there is no definitive answer to this question, though I will later discuss a number of specific strategies which teachers and school districts may employ.Yet, philosophically, ethically, it does seem to me that we can say the following: the gifted are owed what all children are owed, namely, a quality education that adequately challenges them. Defining both adequate and challenge is itself difficult, but we can say this: to be adequately challenged is to be presented with tasks that demand substantial growth in ability, understanding and the ability to flourish, together with the resources and encouragement necessary to succeed in those tasks. Remember that flourishing entails the capacity to freely act upon one’s choices and live them from the inside. Adequate educational Theory and Research in Education 6(1) [ 5 8 ] 086730_TRE_47-70.qxd 2/26/08 10:23 AM Page 58 challenges ought to stimulate a broader range of personal interests (not to the exclusion of communal interests); these supply persons with the sorts of intrinsic benefits that enable critically informed choices and the capacity to identify with a way of life from the inside. Flourishing in this sense is closely related to at least a weak form of autonomy: those who are adequately challenged are more likely to explore and reflect upon the merits of various options and pursuits, and are in that sense autonomous and more likely to lead flourishing lives. Less abstractly, an education that fails to challenge has implications for motiv- ation and learning. Gifted children who lack motivation or interest in school because they are only given educational opportunities challenging enough for ‘average’ learners are less likely to flourish because flourishing is linked to the eagerness to learn. Hence, educational attainment or success in school is directly tied to the level of motivation children experience vis-a-vis the sorts of educational tasks and projects they are given. Now, of course, it may be that some children are so constituted that the knowledge, understanding, skills and virtues that educators aim to impart come rather easily to them, and, even in the absence of a challenging educa- tion, flourish all the same. Neither flourishing nor autonomy is necessarily undermined in the absence of challenge.Yet the ease with which some learners master new challenges misses the point. Merely because some individuals possess the knowledge and skills they need, or manage to do rather well in life despite being seldom challenged in school is no reason to abdicate the respon- sibility to challenge all students. Gifted children, like all children, deserve an education that challenges them. Of course, how to determine what constitutes an adequate challenge and in what ways these challenges are best executed must be decided on a case-by-case basis. So the gifted are at least as deserving of an education that challenges them as more average learners, or learners with disabilities. An education that fails to challenge the gifted – or worse, which facilitates boredom – is no education at all because the main benefit that schools allegedly provide is learning, and to fail to supply this benefit is to vitiate the justification needed for a school’s paternalistic control. Put another way, to be remiss in one’s responsibility to supply an education that adequately challenges children is to show neglect both to the individuals themselves and potentially to others. It is a form of neglect to the gifted because, as I have stressed, an education that fails to adequately challenge may undermine one’s well-being, i.e. one’s ability to flourish, and it is potentially a form of neglect of the well-being of others inasmuch as the absence of cultivated talents and abilities may also be injurious to the well- being of others. Investing additional resources so that the gifted may be adequately challenged, then, is no injustice except when doing so constitutes a form of neglect of others. Nevertheless, the difficulties in determining what Merry: Educational justice and the gifted [ 5 9 ] 086730_TRE_47-70.qxd 2/26/08 10:23 AM Page 59 constitutes an ‘adequate challenge’ will remain unresolved because the means for ascertaining what counts as ‘adequate’ are inescapably contestable.14 Objections In much of the foregoing discussion I have been considering whether special educational provision is justified for gifted children where this involves additional expense.Though adequate challenges for the gifted do not, in many instances, require additional expense (a point I return to), I take up the subject of additional expense both because advocates for gifted education assume this to be necessary, and also because some – albeit rare – cases of exceptional children may warrant it. As I see it, there are at least two reasonably strong objections to increasing monetary allocations that aim to enhance learning opportunities for the gifted. These are: (1) the return on the investment may be too low, and (2) a scarcity of resources precludes dispensing additional resources to learners who suffer no manifest social disadvantages. The first objection says that the investment of additional resources in a gifted student may not yield needed talents or the benefits such talent might lead to. Policy makers (and others) have no way of knowing (a) whether the extra investment will translate into goods or services that benefit the talented individuals in question, or other, less talented, persons, but also (b) whether the gifted would nevertheless achieve the various breakthroughs in human endeavor, even in the absence of special provision. Thus the question arises: if there is not a high probability that education to improve the learning outcomes of the gifted will lead to skills and intelligence that, say, advance new technologies that aid humankind, is the allocation of scarce resources for gifted education defensible? Empirically speaking, it seems reasonable to say that public support for funding gifted programming will likely falter if the allocation of resources shows no obvious benefits.15 The most basic difficulty with this objection is that I argue children deserve an education that adequately challenges them, and a conception of what children deserve is not undermined by the observation that what they deserve does not always produce the benefits hoped for. Another difficulty with this objection is its unreasonably high expectations. Most gifted children cannot reasonably be expected to contribute great things to society, and tying educa- tional provisions to guaranteed, or even probable, outcomes would be worrying for more than the gifted. Indeed, if outcomes must correspond directly with the resources allocated, then we will have a difficult time justifying not only extra provisions for the disabled, but also a free public education to all.16 I trust that additional provision for persons with disabilities needs no further defense here.Yet reasons for a free public education to everyone are also easy Theory and Research in Education 6(1) [ 6 0 ] 086730_TRE_47-70.qxd 2/26/08 10:23 AM Page 60 to locate: the public has an interest in developing the capacity for deliberative and responsible citizenship, as well as expanding opportunities to make informed decisions, including the capacity to select meaningful work and be economically self-reliant. None of these is trivial.Yet with the possible excep- tion of the economic benefits of education – which is demonstrable but in any event is not its principle justification – none of these requires that high school graduates contribute to society in a particular way beyond perhaps minimal civic compliance (e.g. operating within the confines of the law). In a free society, individuals must be allowed to desist from exercising their talents or abilities because, however we may lament the misapplication or neglect of talent and ability, legitimate arrangements in a free society cannot abide compulsion to exercise them. The second objection, that a scarcity of resources precludes dispensing additional resources to learners who suffer no manifest social disadvantages, derives from real-world limitations and budgetary constraints. In a world with limited resources there is often a triage effect in which the administrators of funds must decide whose needs are more pressing. Across the United States, budget deficits have resulted in reduced funding for many educational programs, including music, art, athletics and ‘enrichment’ programming. Conversely, funding for children with disabilities has either increased or remained stagnant. Against this background, advocates for gifted education sometimes argue that the gifted qualify as students with special needs and are therefore deserving of an education that sufficiently challenges them. With IDEA legislation in the background, the demand here is for equity in the form of equality of resources with accompanying pleas for flexible (homogeneous) grouping, adaptive pacing, or supported opportunities to develop the interests of the gifted (Tomlinson 2005;VanTassel-Baska 2005b).Yet the parallels of children with disabilities to gifted children is fraught with difficulties. As previously mentioned, IDEA provided children with physical or cognitive disabilities access to a free education for the first time in American history.The legislation places the burden on the State to fund and provide educational services where previously the burden had fallen almost entirely on parents and their limited resources. Educational services for children with disabilities was a signif- icant advance over what was previously an almost complete absence of educational provision for these children – a flagrant example of discrimination. Yet the justification for educational services for children with disabilities surpasses basic Fourteenth Amendment rights and protections. Some children, owing to the cognitive or physical challenges they face, require infinitely more resources in order to even approach the same opportunities others enjoy.A child who is hard of hearing, for instance, depending on the severity of her condition, will require additional staff, supplemental services such as speech therapy, FM systems, and Merry: Educational justice and the gifted [ 6 1 ] 086730_TRE_47-70.qxd 2/26/08 10:23 AM Page 61 curricular accommodations simply in order for her to glimpse a range of oppor- tunities that come easily to those without hearing loss. So the conflation of the educational needs of the gifted with those of students with disabilities is morally objectionable. Two additional factors must be examined. First, resources for those with disabilities can not be limitless. Reasons may be provided for capping allow- able expenses that a school district is able to spend given the other exigencies with which it must contend. In other words, a school district will not be justified in allocating resources for children with disabilities that are unduly dispro- portionate to what is spent on other students. By ‘unduly disproportionate’ I mean such as would compromise the quality of learning of ‘average’ learners or those who are gifted. Further, for some children with disabilities, enhancing their learning opportunities and thus their quality of life still may be insuf- ficient to surmount the limitations the disability imposes. The severity of the disability may simply disallow significant quality of life improvement. Spending decisions will need to be made on a case-by-case basis using an agreed set of criteria. Second, it is certainly true to say that the gifted face obstacles that lessen their chances of receiving an education that fully develops their potential.Yet given the usually diminished range of capabilities children with physical or cognitive disabilities endure, appeals to maximizing educational opportunities for the gifted (or anyone else) will have little weight.This is because resources are limited and because the cost of maximizing specific types of educational goods for some will likely lead to the neglect of other goods and services (Scheffler, 1985; Gutmann, 1999). Unless gifted children suffer from manifest social disadvantages (and many do), it is far from obvious that children who already possess extraordinary intel- lectual gifts deserve additional resources in order to enhance their learning out- comes when justice may require prioritizing those with learning impediments. However, I have argued that prioritizing any group at the expense of others will conflict with the requirements of educational justice. Of course, justice does not require that educational provisions are equal, only that they are equitable. Provided that all children are receiving an education that adequately challenges them, equitable educational provisions must allow for inequalities that result from the exercise of talents by differently abled and motivated persons. However, given the huge inequities that plague all liberal societies – and some more than others – justice requires that when extra provisions are made to enhance the learning opportunities of highly able persons (and these provisions need not be limited to schools) the justification for doing so must be compelling indeed. I am arguing that the need to adequately challenge all children in the education they receive may be that justification, even as we note that doing so may be expensive. (However, as I shall note in the next section, many of the Theory and Research in Education 6(1) [ 6 2 ] 086730_TRE_47-70.qxd 2/26/08 10:23 AM Page 62 gifted can be adequately challenged in ways that require no additional expense.) Of course, state policies and services that aim to abolish endemic inequities such as child poverty would go a much greater distance in achieving justice. For many, poverty – and its correlates like poor health – impair even the will to learn let alone the capacities to be educationally developed. Nevertheless, no amount of justice will remove the differences in motivation and talent that distinguish persons from one another. Ideally, gains that result from providing the exceptionally able with adequate challenge should also redound to others, and perhaps especially those whose environmental conditions have precluded access to similar opportunities, or whose physical or cognitive endowments have been shortchanged in the natural lottery. However, I have shown that many obstacles may foil such favorable out- comes, not the least of which is that gifted persons may abstain from exercising their talents and gifts in ways that benefit others. p r a c t i c a l c o n c e r n s When cases come to light which suggest unusually high ability in more than one area, it will need to be determined how best to organize learning opportun- ities to serve these students. In some instances, a case may need to be made for altogether separate and advanced instruction.This may take the form of college coursework, independent study, private tutoring or home-schooling, even at the State’s expense. In many cases schools simply will not have the trained staff or resources to adequately challenge exceptionally abled children. Yet given the difficulties in defining giftedness that I discussed earlier in this article, determining which children qualify in each subject will remain contested territory. I have focused on a fairly broad interpretation of cognitive ability in part because far more difficult cases involve diagnosing unusual affective or intuitive ability. A clear case might be a nine-year-old who demonstrates advanced mathematical ability in trigonometry, for instance. Whatever the case, the difficulties do not disappear once unusual ability is ascertained. It will remain to be seen whether further investment of energies ought to be given to developing other, as yet unrealized, areas of ability, and it will also need to be determined whether the school possesses the resources to adequately challenge such a pupil or whether recommending services beyond what the school can provide is appropriate. It is important to remember that we are likely talking about an extremely small per- centage of children who are of school age. Most evidence suggests that the vast majority of children currently enjoying high ability homogeneous grouping or gifted and talented programming in American public schools do not qualify for the simple reason that most of these children are not so much gifted as they are socially privileged (Borland, 2005; Ford and Harris, 1999). Merry: Educational justice and the gifted [ 6 3 ] 086730_TRE_47-70.qxd 2/26/08 10:23 AM Page 63 Separate and/or advanced instruction for the few whose extraordinary abil- ities surpass their peers by many years will not remove the temptation for socially privileged parents to apply pressure to school administrators to allow their child to participate. Many of these will be parents who are already accus- tomed to having their way with school administrators and believe that their children are more special than ‘other people’s children’. To avoid the inevitable demands wealthier and more educated parents will make, clear rules will need to be drawn up, multiple diagnostic systems will need to be in place, and State oversight will need to ensure that fair procedures are consistently applied. In order to optimize the prospect of children interacting with others of varying abilities, preferences, perspectives and the like, a number of researchers have made compelling arguments for well-planned heterogeneous grouping, as well as curricular choice and multi-age classrooms which allow teachers more flexibility in scaffolding learning opportunities less in accordance with grade-level expectations and more closely allied to individual interests. There is no point in denying that some children learn faster than others or possess a knowledge base that exceeds those of their peers. But homogeneous grouping and separate provisions for faster learners is a poor way of addressing differences among students.17 The effects for children who are grouped low include all of the problems associated with stigmatization and disadvantage: lower self-image, alienation from learning and from school, and resentment towards classmates who advance in school at their expense (Davies et al., 2003; Ireson and Hallam, 2005; Lucas, 1999). The answer to these challenges is not that quick learners should be punished or ‘held back’ so that the learning opportunities of slower learners are ensured. Rather, where it is used, class- room grouping must be equitably structured to benefit all learners. Of course, adequately challenging all learners is easier said than done. In all areas, including education, this requires more than simply removing the formal barriers of discrimination. For starters it will require that school adminis- trators and teachers become better attuned to the learning needs of the stu- dents they teach. This may include more culturally relevant curricula and teaching methods, but also more effective and consistent efforts to connect with the students’ parents.18 And it will most certainly require adequately challenging all children irrespective of their socialization, personality, or set of preferences. Adequate challenges may take several forms, including: cluster grouping/ ‘enriched learning’ in specific subjects; extracurricular programs; alternative scheduling patterns; mentorships; combined classes; self-paced instruction; concept- or problem-based learning; non-graded classrooms; grade skipping or acceleration; grade telescoping (i.e. time compression of junior/senior high school curriculum); and early college entrance (Renzulli, 2005;VanTassel-Baska, 2005b). Theory and Research in Education 6(1) [ 6 4 ] 086730_TRE_47-70.qxd 2/26/08 10:23 AM Page 64 Some (Purdy, 2007) have argued that accelerated learning opportunities simply make good economic sense, while others (Clark, 2005) suggest that leveling or flexible grouping (combined with multilevel reading selections and opportunities for in-depth research and group projects) better serves all students. However, typically these recommendations are made available only to children deemed to be ‘gifted’. Yet, with the possible exception of grade telescoping, grade skipping and early college enrollment, all children can benefit from the differentiated instruction proposals above.That several of these require a departure from the status quo is no reason to sidestep the responsibility to pursue them. Good teachers look for ways to expand opportunities for student self-selection; know how to exploit mentorships; maintain high expectations; use a variety of resources and instructional strategies; and employ continuous and varied assess- ment tools. Most of these involve no additional expenditure. c o n c l u s i o n s In this article I have specifically examined two questions. First, in asking what constitutes a gifted person I have cast doubt on whether giftedness as it is presently conceptualized is sufficient justification for maintaining high ability grouping or separate gifted instruction. I have also examined whether children with unusual abilities can be compared with those with disabilities and have found the comparison wanting. Second, I have examined whether gifted children are owed additional educational provisions as a matter of justice. I have shown that the gifted may be adequately challenged in schools without additional expense but that some cases clearly warrant alternative solutions that may incur additional cost. Above all, I have argued that gifted children deserve to be adequately challenged as much as anyone else – so long as those challenges do not compromise the education of other children – because, to a significant degree, their ability to flourish hinges on it.Therefore, whether teachers facilitate adequate educational challenges for all children is a matter of paramount ethical importance. When denied an education that challenges them, all children, including the gifted, suffer neglect. I have conceded that determining whether a child has been adequately challenged is indeterminate partly because its meaning must be decided upon in different times and places according to the availability of resources, the complexity and specificity of needs, and the political will to address those needs. I have also pointed out that various incentives, methods and programs may be used to adequately challenge students; further, meaningful assessments will need to be developed to indicate with some degree of reliability whether students have demonstrated significant growth. Where reliable diagnostics determine actual cases of exceptionality, staff will need to determine whether that student can realistically be well served in the public school or whether she is better served Merry: Educational justice and the gifted [ 6 5 ] 086730_TRE_47-70.qxd 2/26/08 10:23 AM Page 65 elsewhere. Either way, justice will require that such a student is adequately challenged even as we must concede that what is meant precisely by ‘adequately challenged’ remains, for the moment, an unsettled matter. Gifted or not, no child deserves merely the educational minimum;19 rather, each child deserves to be educated in ways that stimulate and provoke critical thinking and creativity regardless of parental input, teacher recommendation and test scores. Yet, currently, more needs to be done to distinguish the truly gifted from the socially privileged. Ending grouping practices and programming that favor the children of the socially privileged will require administrative back- bone, instructional differentiation, and generally more planning and effort – there’s no getting around that.Yet, if teachers are attuned to the needs of their students, classroom instruction can be arranged so that learning opportunities are enhanced (though not maximized) for all children and not just a lucky few. And what is education for in the first place, if not to foster the intellectual and developmental growth of all children according to their individual needs? a c k n o w l e d g e m e n t s I am grateful to Eamonn Callan, Randall Curren, Doret de Ruyter, Michael Hand and Charles Howell for their useful feedback, and also to Bill New and Matt Tedesco for comments on an earlier draft. n o t e s 1. In 1990, the Americans with Disabilities Act was passed, moving the protection of persons with disabilities further into the public sphere. Exceptions remained in the private sphere.Thus private schools are not held to the requirements of the legislation. In 1997, the Act was reinstated with a few more provisions. 2. Trends in the United Kingdom appear to be moving in the opposite direction. The British schools minister Lord Adonis announced recently that the bright- est 5 per cent of pupils are to have their names entered into a national register. All secondary schools in the United Kingdom will receive letters encouraging teachers to recommend the names of pupils they wish to be entered into a database for gifted and talented so that their progress can be tracked as they move through school. Children are to be selected according to both academic test results as well as abilities in music, drama, dance and sport. Though the stated aim of the British government is to widen access for pupils from poorer backgrounds, the outcry against the initiative by teachers’ unions and education theorists suggests that a national register will give middle-class parents even more reason to pressure their children to succeed on high stakes exams, as well as pressure school officials to select their children. See Cassidy (2006). 3. In fact, more than 30 states have legislation providing special programming for gifted learners. 4. Of course, parents of the gifted do not usually object to special services being provided for children of poor families; they merely ask that the schools their Theory and Research in Education 6(1) [ 6 6 ] 086730_TRE_47-70.qxd 2/26/08 10:23 AM Page 66 children attend provide the kinds of differentiated instruction that will suffi- ciently challenge them. 5. This is a bold and controversial claim for which there is no conclusive proof.The basis for my claim is threefold: (1) the available (albeit conflicting) studies which suggest that truly exceptional children are quite rare; (2) my experience as a teacher, researcher and a staff member in four separate schools districts of varying size; finally, (3) my professional experience with socially privileged undergradu- ates, many of whom have undeservedly received the gifted label in high schools. In fact, there are no reliable statistics available suggesting what percentage of the population is exceptionally able. However, a fairly significant percentage of chil- dren manage to enjoy the gifted label in American schools. Davidson and Davidson (2004:18) write:‘As many as one in six American students between the ages of four and eighteen – some 10 million young people – receive this label [gifted] for scoring one standard deviation or more above the norm on intelli- gence tests.’ Incidentally, this is consistent with the figures emanating from the United Kingdom, where a recent report from Wales indicated that 27 per cent of school children were assessed as ‘having more academic ability’. See Isaac (2006). Even so, of the 62 million school-age children in the United States, only 62 thou- sand have IQs over 145, a fairly small number. See Cloud (2007). 6. Gardner himself rejects the association of multiple intelligences with claims for gifted education (1999: 89), though this has not prevented gifted advocates from appropriating his theory. 7. T. M. Scanlon (1995: 112–13) notes that well-being relates to ‘an idea of the quality of a life for the person who lives it that is broader than material and social conditions, at least potentially broader than experiential quality, differ- ent from worthiness or value, and narrower than choiceworthiness all things considered.’ John White (2007) adds that well-being is desire dependent, cul- turally specific and circumscribed by a loose collection of people. Further, the ‘most authoritative voices on what constitutes our well-being are among those with a wide acquaintance with all sorts of goods’ (White, 2007: 23). 8. Naturally, parental involvement varies considerably. While stereotypes seldom allow for it, the fact remains that many poor parents invest immeasurably in their child’s education while many a wealthy parent is indisposed and uninterested. 9. Each of these vocations implies a significant amount of social prestige. Many others not mentioned here are unquestionably complex roles requiring unusual ability.The skills many short-order cooks and administrative assistants possess seem to me to be illustrative examples. 10. I am not interested to settle here whether it is justifiable for wealthy parents to ensure certain advantages for their children. Compelling arguments tug in opposite directions concerning what the proper bounds of parental advocacy entail. See the discussions in Swift (2003) and Archard and Macleod (2002). My interest here is merely to point out the manner in which some parents provide advantages for their children that potentially harm other children. 11. This may take a variety of forms, including a progressive tax code carefully designed to benefit the less-advantaged. Merry: Educational justice and the gifted [ 6 7 ] 086730_TRE_47-70.qxd 2/26/08 10:23 AM Page 67 12. Rawls’ formulation requires both that the Liberty Principle (i.e. the first prin- ciple of justice) as well as the principle of equality of opportunity be lexically prior to the DP. The Liberty Principle states that ‘each person has the same indefeasible claim to a fully adequate scheme of equal liberties, which scheme is compatible with the same scheme of liberties for all’ (Rawls, 2001: 42). Lexical priority means that the conditions for the former must first be satis- fied before opportunities are to be arranged that benefit the least advantaged. This means that the least advantaged are not to be prioritized if and when liberty is infringed upon, such as when some persons with disabilities argue that medical intervention is an affront to their autonomy. Indeed, many persons with disabilities exercise their basic liberty in refusing corrective measures (e.g. cochlear implants).Therefore, left on its own the DP is hamstrung, for Rawls’ second axiom of justice clearly allows for inequalities that result from the exercise of talents owned by differently abled and motivated persons. 13. For example, Rawls’ theory assumes that all persons operating within a system of fair cooperation operate ‘within the normal range’ of functioning, and the moral powers on which this system is based are described entirely in cog- nitive terms, thus seeming to exclude those with severe mental impairments. For a recent critique of Rawls on exactly this point, see Nussbaum (2006). 14. Asking children whether they feel adequately challenged will prove as unre- liable as administering tests that some will interpret to mean that high scorers are not being challenged enough. 15. With little difficulty one could catalogue a long list of tragic Western artists and intellectuals whose talents and abilities did little more than facilitate egoistic and fruitless pursuits while bringing untold suffering onto others whose lives they shared. 16. Due to the inequitable effects of funding schemes, local control, racist lega- cies and the vagaries of personal circumstance, equality of opportunity remains an unrealized ideal, but its promise nonetheless is embedded in the justification for its provision in the first place. 17. Most studies – inside and outside the United States – suggest that homoge- neous ability grouping benefits high end learners. See Desbottes and Nicholls (n.d.); Gamoran (1986, 1992); Ireson and Hallam (2005). Other studies produce conflicting results.Whatever the level of perceived ability, many believe that the pace of instruction, matched to students of like perceived ability, may provide opportunities to accelerate or reinforce the necessary skills students need to acquire. Nevertheless, critics contend that grouping greatly disad- vantages students lacking in the skills other children bring to school by virtue of their social class background. 18. Clearly smaller districts with a low mobility rate will have an easier time with this. 19. Nevertheless, the current emphasis on ‘proficiency’ in the US under the No Child Left Behind Act (2002) accords well with the Supreme Court senti- ment that the State is not required to provide an ideal education but merely a basic education. Hence, the allocation of resources to move students beyond proficiency is simply not on the table. Theory and Research in Education 6(1) [ 6 8 ] 086730_TRE_47-70.qxd 2/26/08 10:23 AM Page 68 r e f e r e n c e s Archard, D. and Macleod, C., eds (2002) The Moral and Political Status of Children. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Borland, J. H. (2005) ‘Gifted education without gifted children: The case for no conception of giftedness’, in R. Sternberg and J. Davidson (eds), Conceptions of Giftedness, pp. 1–19. New York: Cambridge University Press. Borland, J. H. and Wright, L. (1994) ‘Identifying and educating poor and underrep- resented gifted students’, in K. A. Heller, F. J. Monks, R. J. Sternberg and R. F. Subotnik (eds), International Handbook of Research and Development of Giftedness and Talent, pp. 164–171. London: Pergamon Press. Callahan, C. M. and Miller, E. M. (2005) ‘A child-responsive model of giftedness’, in R. Sternberg and J. Davidson (eds), Conceptions of Giftedness, pp. 38–51. New York: Cambridge University Press. Cassidy, S. (2006) ‘Do bright children need to be taught separately, and is it good for them?’, The Independent (12 July): 31. Clark, L. (2005) ‘Gifted and growing’. Educational Leadership 63(3): 56–60. Cloud, J. (2007) Failing our geniuses. Time (27 August): 41–6. Davidson, J. and Davidson, B. (2004) Genius Denied: How to Stop Wasting our Brightest Young Minds. New York: Simon & Schuster. Davies, J., Hallan, S. and Ireson, J. (2003) ‘Ability groupings in the primary school: Issues arising from practice’, Research Papers in Education 18(1): 45–60. Desbottes, A. and Nicholls, T. (n.d.) ‘What is the impact of cross-phase, cross- curricular learning on gifted and talented pupils?’, Education Review 18(1): 79–84. Ford, D.Y. and Harris, J. J. (1999) Multicultural Gifted Education. New York:Teachers College Press. Gamoran, A. (1986) ‘Instructional and institutional effects of ability grouping’, Sociology of Education 59: 185–98. Gamoran, A. (1992) ‘Is ability grouping equitable?’, Education Leadership 58(7):11–17. Gardner, H. (1999) Intelligence Reframed. New York: Basic Books. Gordon, E. W. and Bridglall, B. L. (2005) ‘Nurturing talent in gifted students of color’, in R. Sternberg and J. Davidson (eds), Conceptions of Giftedness., pp. 120–146. New York: Cambridge University Press. Gutmann, A. (1999) Democratic Education, 2nd edn. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Harry, B. and Klingner J. (2006) Why Are There so many Minority Students in Special Education? Understanding Race and Disability. New York:Teachers College Press. Heller, K. A., Perleth, C. and Lim, T.K. (2005) ‘The Munich model of giftedness designed to identify and promote gifted students’, in R. Sternberg and J. Davidson (eds), Conceptions of Giftedness, pp. 147–170. New York: Cambridge University Press. Ireson, J. and Hallam, S. (2005) ‘Pupils’ liking for school: Ability grouping, self- concept and perceptions of teaching’, British Journal of Educational Psychology 75: 297–311. Isaac, J. (2006) ‘A talent for doing best for the gifted’, The Times Educational Supplement Cymru (7 July): 5. Lareau, A. (2002) ‘Invisible inequality: social class and childrearing in black fami- lies and white families’, American Sociological Review 67(5): 747–76. Merry: Educational justice and the gifted [ 6 9 ] 086730_TRE_47-70.qxd 2/26/08 10:23 AM Page 69 Losen, D. J. and Orfield, G. (2002) Racial Inequity in Special Education. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Education Press. Lucas, S. (1999) Tracking Inequality: Stratification and Mobility in American High Schools. New York:Teachers College Press. Moore, J., Ford, D. and Milner, H. R. (2005) ‘Underachievement among gifted stu- dents of color: implications for educators’, Theory into Practice 44(2): 167–77. Nussbaum, M. (2006) Frontiers of Justice: Disability, Nationality, Species Membership. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Ogbu, J. (2003) Black American Students in an Affluent Suburb: A Study of Academic Disengagement. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Purdy, L, (2007) ‘Educating gifted children’, in R. Curren (ed.), Philosophy of Education: An Anthology, pp. 314–19. Oxford: Blackwell. Rawls, J. (2001) Justice as Fairness: A Restatement. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Renzulli, J (2005) ‘Applying gifted education pedagogy to total talent develop- ment for all students’, Theory into Practice 44(2): 80–9. Rothstein, R. (2004) Class and Schools: Using Social, Economic, and Educational Reform to Close the Black-White Achievement Gap. New York:Teachers College Press. Scanlon, T. M. (1995) What We Owe Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Scheffler, I. (1985) Of Human Potential: An Essay in the Philosophy of Education. Boston: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Swift, A. (2003) How not to be a Hypocrite: School Choice for the Morally-Perplexed Parent. London: Routledge. Tomlinson, C. A. (2005) ‘Quality curriculum and instruction for highly able stu- dents’, Theory into Practice 44(2): 160–6. VanTassel-Baska, J. (2005a) ‘Domain-specific giftedness’, in R. Sternberg and J. Davidson (eds), Conceptions of Giftedness, pp. 358–376. New York: Cambridge University Press. VanTassel-Baska, J. (2005b) ‘Gifted programs and services: What are the non- negotiables?’, Theory into Practice 44(2): 90–97. White, J. (2007) ‘Well-being and education: issues of culture and authority’, Journal of Philosophy of Education 41(1): 17–28. Winstanley, C. (2003) Too Clever by Half: A Fair Deal for Gifted Children. Stoke on Trent:Trentham Books. b i o g r a p h i c a l n o t e m i c h a e l s . m e r r y is visiting professor in educational studies at Beloit College and is the author of many articles in the philosophy of education. He is also the author of Culture, Identity and Islamic Schooling: a philosophical approach. [email: merrym@beloit.edu] Theory and Research in Education 6(1) [ 7 0 ] 086730_TRE_47-70.qxd 2/26/08 10:23 AM Page 70 work_7oqukvc7wbfz7jcfpw6dbqqdnq ---- 1 Running head: SEQUENCING JUSTICE SEQUENCING JUSTICE: A LONGITUDINAL STUDY OF JUSTICE GOALS OF DOMESTIC VIOLENCE VICTIMS Robyn L. Holder and Kathleen Daly Griffith University, Australia Authors’ Note Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to Robyn Holder, Griffith Criminology Institute, Griffith University, Mt Gravatt Campus, 176 Messines Ridge Road, Mt Gravatt, Queensland 4122, Australia. Phone: +61 (0) 7 3735 3440 Fax: +61 (0) 7 3735 6812 E- mail: r.holder@griffith.edu.au This is a pre-publication version. The published article is available in The British Journal of Criminology, azx046, https://doi.org/10.1093/bjc/azx046 (published online, 28 September 2017) and see https://academic.oup.com/bjc/issue © Robyn Holder and Kathleen Daly 20 July 2017 mailto:r.holder@griffith.edu.au https://doi.org/10.1093/bjc/azx046 https://academic.oup.com/bjc/issue 2 SEQUENCING JUSTICE: A LONGITUDINAL STUDY OF JUSTICE GOALS OF DOMESTIC VIOLENCE VICTIMS Abstract What women as victims of domestic violence want from criminal justice has long interested researchers and advocates. This article foregrounds the ways in which ‘justice’ matters to victims and how a desire for justice may change over time. We find that victims have multiple justice goals, which are ordered and unfold through the criminal justice process. The goals are directed towards three domains of victim, offender and community; and are influenced by both personal and public interests. Accountability is a threshold goal from which others—punishment, deterrence, rehabilitation or another—may be contemplated. From the perspective of victims, achieving justice is sequencing these goals through hybrid processes with differing degrees of victim participation. Keywords Justice goals, justice interests, longitudinal design, domestic violence 3 SEQUENCING JUSTICE: A LONGITUDINAL STUDY OF JUSTICE GOALS OF DOMESTIC VIOLENCE VICTIMS Funding This work was supported by an ANU Miscellaneous Scholarship; a Regulatory Institutions PhD Scholarship; the Audrey Fagan Post Graduate Scholarship; and an Australian Research Council Discovery Grant [grant number DP130103775]. Acknowledgements We are indebted to the women who shared their experiences and to the Domestic Violence Crisis Service, Canberra, for helping make this possible. The first author would also like to thank Peter Grabosky for his guidance and support. 4 SEQUENCING JUSTICE: A LONGITUDINAL STUDY OF JUSTICE GOALS OF DOMESTIC VIOLENCE VICTIMS What women as victims of domestic violence want from criminal justice has long interested researchers and advocates. Yet women’s preferences are often analysed and understood as competing choices, that is, between a substantive outcome or procedural justice, between conventional or restorative justice, and between private or public justice amongst others (for review, see Daly and Stubbs 2006). The key problem is that evidence on this question is gathered at a single point in time. The desires for justice are more complex, in part, because they unfold over time and in different socio-legal contexts. To understand ‘what women want’ from criminal justice is better captured with a prospective longitudinal design. This article presents interviews with women on three occasions after their victimization by a male partner or ex-partner, and at different points in the criminal justice process.1 It finds that the women have multiple justice goals and prefer to realize them through hybrid processes—a phenomenon we term ‘sequencing justice’. We build on Gromet and Darley’s (2009: 2, 4) insight that people have a ‘full range of justice concerns’ and ‘the ultimate goal of achieving justice’ is reached by the progressive realization of sub-goals. Their laboratory research concluded that achieving justice was not accomplished by punishment of the offender alone (2009: 29), but that people were equally concerned with other objectives. In ‘real world’ research on female victims of domestic violence, studies have provided snapshots of women’s experiences of police (Hirschel and Hutchison 2003; Hoyle and Sanders 2000), prosecution (Hare 2006), and courts (Bell et al. 2011), and their attitudes towards and satisfaction with criminal justice overall (Barata 2007; Erez and Belknap 5 1998; Fleury 2002; Smith 2001). However, no study to date has sought to determine women’s expectations of and goals for justice from the beginning to the end of the criminal justice process. Some have interviewed women on two occasions: a US study identified women’s concerns with how their case was handled in court (Bell et al. 2011), and a Scottish study explored how women engaged the justice system to constrain a violent partner (Lewis et al. 2000). Other US studies have interviewed women on three occasions (Fleury-Steiner et al. 2006; McFarlane et al. 2000). However, all these studies were retrospective.2 To date, none has used a prospective design,3 which reports women’s views and goals as their case moves through a legal process. Our study is the first to do so. It draws on the routines of criminal justice in an Australian jurisdiction—from reporting to police, to prosecution and through to the criminal court. At each stage in the process, women were asked what they wanted, why their goals were important, and what their preferred processes were to achieve the goals. Their responses were grounded in a multi-dimensional understanding of justice. Women, violence and justice Justice is a complex idea with many different associations (Sen 2009). It is a philosophical and juridical concept and a core social value. Dispensing justice is a primary function of legal institutions. There has been a tendency by researchers, policy makers and activists to assume the aspirations for justice of victims of domestic violence. An early and primary concern critiqued the state’s reluctance to enforce the norms of criminal law when confronted with domestic 6 violence (Dobash and Dobash 1992). Yet it soon became apparent that criminal justice was not always experienced by women as a benevolent force for good (Snider 1998). Searches for better or more effective ‘alternatives’ argued that the ‘conflict’ between private persons did not belong to the state in the first place (Christie 1977; Mills 1999) and that stronger (or more punitive) criminal justice responses created a dead-end for all concerned (Zehr 1990). The idea of diversion and restorative justice appeared to offer a radical departure (Strang 2002). An emphasis on responding to the harm of victimization was shared by those interested in therapeutic jurisprudence (Wemmers 2008), and reinforced by the conceptual framing of victim viewpoints and preferences as ‘needs’ (Herman 2005). The literature debating these approaches in response to gendered violence has become vast (Daly and Stubbs 2006), but in the process, the meanings of justice for victims became lost in searches for responses that were least harmful to them. Contemporary criminal justice has long been acknowledged as unsupportive of victims, but there is little evidence that healing and restoration are what domestic violence victims seek from state justice (Hare 2006). In their interactions with justice authorities, women victimized by domestic violence are similar to victims of other crimes in desiring to be treated with courtesy and fairness (Van Camp and Wemmers 2013). In addition, domestic violence victims generally initiate police intervention (Felson et al. 2005; Holder 2007). Focusing on women’s agency in initiating the involvement of authorities invites attention to their ‘active negotiation and strategic resistance both with their partners and with a range of helping agencies’ (Lewis et al. 2000: 180). In this light, women are making ‘justice claims’ (Daly and Stubbs 2006: 19-22). But, claims for what? The waves of debate return to the question of what justice women seek when they mobilize the law following domestic violence. 7 A number of scholars suggest that perhaps ‘justice’ is not viewed in a singular manner. As one of us says elsewhere, there are ‘intermingled’ aspirations for justice that may be meaningful in different ways and at different times (Daly 2000; see also Sen 2009). Part of the problem in knowing what justice women seek is methodological. Most studies ask women for their retrospective opinions (Herman 2005). Others enquire at different levels of analysis. For example, in some studies, women may be asked what justice they sought in their particular case (McGillivray and Comaskey 1999), whereas other studies ask women their general opinion about reform options for justice responses to domestic violence (Nancarrow 2006; Rubin 2010). Part of the problem is also conceptual. Some studies prioritize offender desistance as the objective of criminal justice (Visher et al. 2008) and others emphasize victim concerns (Barata 2007; Hare 2006). The array of justice practices, different experiences of victimization and diverse data collection problems have generated a rich, but confusing scholarship. In recognising the different ways that justice is understood and its institutions are experienced, researchers and advocates now acknowledge that, as agents, female victims of domestic violence are not limited to identities as ‘female’ or ‘victim’ alone. Rather, women are situated in differing and overlapping ways in social and political spaces, and with multiple relationships to authorities. From this perspective, we suggest that women making claims on public authorities for justice hold and project ‘interests’ in justice (Holder 2013/2018). The term conveys a broader and less personal justice lens than the term ‘needs’. It assumes that victims not only have a relationship with a violent person, but are also in a relation to state authorities. This is not to deny that victims of violence have needs, especially for safety and recovery (Minaker 2001). It is to say that when engaging public justice and looking through a broad justice frame, 8 additional aspirations and concerns are engaged, and as a consequence, multifaceted viewpoints emerge. In responding to these challenges, this study does not attempt to define a ‘successful’ intervention for women as victims of domestic violence or identify what makes them safer or more satisfied (Holder 2015). Nor does it delineate the contours of a particular model of justice. Rather, it provides a unique empirical exploration of women’s preferences—as justice sub-goals (Gromet and Darley 2009)—at the beginning of the regular criminal process and again at its later stages, and the meanings they bring to the idea of justice. A longitudinal prospective study The study’s methods are described more fully elsewhere (Holder 2013/2018, 2016) but in brief, women were interviewed on three occasions following their violent victimization by a male partner or ex-partner. The women, aged over 18 years, were a purposive sample invited to participate in the research through their contact with a domestic violence service. Data collection occurred over four years, from 2009 to 2013. The Time 1 interview took place after the police decided to charge the assailant with a criminal offence. This interview asked each woman why she had turned to the law, with what motivations and expectations, and what she wanted the court to decide. These court options were not hypothetical, but drawn from the study jurisdiction’s sentencing legislation. Women were also asked why they wanted those objectives, what they hoped to achieve, and what type of process they would prefer in order to attain those objectives. The Time 2 interview took place after the case had finished in court. Each woman was asked what she then thought about the decisions and outcomes made by the prosecution and by 9 the court, and why she held that view. Each was then asked again about the type of process she would have liked. The time between the first and second interviews varied. The shortest time was two months and the longest was 24 months. The wait time for the second interview depended on when each individual case was finalized at court. The Time 3 interview was conducted six to eight months after the case had finished in court. Each woman was asked what she now thought about justice, in particular, whether justice was done and why.4 The longitudinal design facilitated real time attention to women’s different engagements with and judgements of law enforcement, prosecution, and court as distinct criminal justice entities. Longitudinal prospective studies are infrequent, in part, because they are difficult to carry out with both recruitment and retention problems (Plano Clark et al. 2014). These were mitigated by the first author’s long-standing relationships with justice and community agencies in the study jurisdiction.5 Nonetheless, sample attrition occurred. The study began with 27 participants at Time 1, which reduced to 21 at Time 2, and 14 at Time 3 (52% of the original number). Our analysis of attrition finds no substantial differences (that is, 10 percentage points or more)6 for those interviewed in Times 1 and 2 on socio-economic variables and those measuring personal agency, orientations to trust in institutions and in the law, relationship type and longevity, frequency or escalation of violence, or desires to continue the relationship. However, when moving from Time 1 to Time 2 and 3, an increasing share of women initiated the report to the police (67% to 76% and 86%) and a decreasing share wanted the police to make an arrest (from 44% to 33% and 21%). Differences were evident in the socio-economic profile for those at Time 3, compared to those interviewed once or twice. The Time 3 group was more likely to be tertiary educated and working in a white-collar occupation,7 a profile consistent with retention in longitudinal studies of women’s health (Young et al. 2006). In addition, the Time 3 group was in 10 a shorter-term relationship with the assailant (less than five years); they were less likely to want the court to sentence the offender to community service or to receive a written apology. However, for all three groups, there was consistency in their sentence priority for treatment outcomes. Our primary focus in this article is on those interviewed twice because it permits us to compare the same group of women over time. However, we shall also present selected findings from the Time 3 interview because they offer reflections on ‘the idea of justice’ more broadly. The demographic profile of the 21 women interviewed reflects that of the study jurisdiction, a generally affluent and educated population. The city hosts both federal and state government bureaucracies and four universities. Most women (67%) were in paid employment, full or part-time; and 38% of those employed were in white collar jobs. Equal proportions (48%) earned under AUD $45,000 and between AUD $45,000 and $100,000.8 Nearly all were Australian born (86%) although none was an Indigenous Australian, 43% had a university degree, and most (67%) had children living at home. The 21 participants were unusual in that all the assailants were arrested and their cases proceeded to criminal court; of these, all but two were prosecuted.9 Most domestic violence is not reported to authorities in Australia (Cox 2016), a finding similar to that for the United Kingdom (UK) (Walby and Allen 2004), the United States (Felson et al 2005), and Canada (Johnson 2006). When it is, police diversion of domestic violence to ‘out of court resolution’ may be more widespread than previously thought. For example, every police force in the UK except Scotland was found to divert domestic violence cases away from formal criminal justice resolution, despite a uniform police policy advising against it (Westmarland et al 2017). However, Garner and Maxwell’s (2009) review of a number of countries find that 34% of 11 reported offences proceed to prosecution, and when assailants are arrested, 59% proceed to prosecution, albeit with considerable jurisdictional variation. At the time of the incident that prompted police involvement, 52% of the women were in a relationship of five years or more standing. A majority (57%) were in a relationship with a husband or de facto who was the assailant. For 48% of the women this was the first time that they had sought help from police, but 29% had a protection order in place at the time of the incident. A majority (62%) said their situation was worsening. Before this most recent occasion of reported abuse, all but three of the 21 women had been abused previously by the assailant, with 43% (of N=18) saying that the abuse had happened ‘quite a few’ or ‘many’ times before. The experiences and accounts of the women are presented moving from the Time 1 to Time 3 interview. The first section describes 21 women’s general expectations of criminal justice at Time 1, and their specific aims and reasons in calling for police assistance. It describes their prospective preferences on the goals they sought from prosecution and the court and through what process. The next gives women’s retrospective assessments of the decisions actually reached by prosecution and court personnel at Time 2. The third section presents the women’s reflections about six to eight months after the case was finalized in court, with an analysis of 14 cases at Time 3. Time 1: Police Intervention Mobilizing law and accountability Turning to the law after domestic violence is not an obvious choice for many victims. However, like other research (Felson et al 2005; Holder 2007), most women initiated the call to police.10 All of them agreed with the statement that police viewed what happened to them as serious and 12 most felt that ‘the community’ shared this standpoint. Many expressed a sense of social support in calling police and drew on public discourse that ‘domestic violence is a crime’. Indeed, the study jurisdiction has pro-arrest and pro-prosecution policies, which may have influenced women’s views and decisions (Novisky and Peralta 2015). For example, Aimee11 said she ‘knew [it] was illegal, a crime. It was obvious to me … I just knew that this was not on and that the best way of dealing with it was to go to the police’. The women’s most common aims for police intervention were stopping the violence and a desire to be safe. Others wanted to get help for themselves or simply ‘to get out of there’. These are self-regarding motivations. In addition, the women said it was for the offender that they called police. Ursula wanted her husband ‘to get help’. Teresa said that she wanted her ex- partner ‘to know he was doing the wrong thing’. This type of language depicts offender-related objectives. Women were also motivated to protect others: their children, significant others and the public. With respect to children, Cathy expressed concern that ‘it happened in front of [our son] and I was hit in the stomach and was afraid for the baby. I was not having [our son] grow up thinking it’s okay’.12 Olivia was ‘fearful for the other person’ she was now involved with. In all three timeframes the women spoke in different ways about a trilogy of justice interests: for themselves, the offender and their community of others.13 Although most women had initiated the call to police, seven wanted an arrest made, five did not, and the rest were unsure or wanted other actions taken. Despite a degree of ambivalence, only five women said that they subsequently asked that charges arising from the incident be dropped. One did so because she felt her husband was mentally unwell, another because she felt shared culpability for the incident, another because she felt the arrest was sufficient to produce 13 changes in behaviour, and two because they were emotionally attached to and concerned for the violent person. Structuring their reasoning were strong views that the abuse was wrong. They used different expressions to say the violence was unacceptable and should not be swept ‘under the rug’. The violent person ‘needs to wake up’ and should ‘not get away with it’. They felt the ‘truth’ should be known; that the violent person ‘should know better, know what’s right and wrong’. On these points of wrongfulness, women asked that the violent person ‘accept responsibility’ and ‘be accountable for [his] actions’. These words comprised the elements of accountability, a hope that women repeated in their first interview and which grew in later interviews. Offender accountability served as a bridging concept from the situational drive to call the police to stop the violence and women’s contemplation of the justice process that lay ahead. Prospective justice goals All but two women expected that the justice system would be fair, an expectation that was also found in two US studies (Barata 2007; Bell et al. 2011). Women’s specific thinking about outcomes was probed in several ways. Looking ahead to the court process, they were asked what decision they would like the magistrate or judge to make, what sentence outcome they would prefer, and what principles of justice they thought were important to apply to their case. With 17 relevant sentence options in the jurisdiction’s legislation and nine possible justice principles, the interview kept definitions as simple as possible. For example, the principle of punishment was described as doing ‘something to punish/discipline/penalize/chastise the person’, and the principle of restoration was doing ‘something to recognize the harm caused and to help restore all parties’. 14 Of the 21 women, most (76%, N=16) wanted the court to render a guilty finding, and its meaning was simple: ‘he did it’, said Holly. The reason for her preference was ‘he’ll just keep doing it and think he can get away with it’. Two said they were neither in favour nor against a guilty finding. For the three women who did not want a guilty finding, all indicated that they wanted their relationship with the violent person to continue and they made mitigating comment on his behalf. Roslyn’s partner had previously been convicted of assaulting her. She shared a small business with him and wanted her relationship with him to continue. Although she had not wanted an arrest or guilty finding, she hoped to see, at some point, ‘an admission of responsibility for his actions’. Of the five who said that they had not wanted the violent person arrested, most said that they favoured a guilty finding. After stating a preference for a guilty finding, the women indicated the sentence outcome they favoured. They could choose more than one option as ‘essential, the highest priority’. Preferences clustered strongly for sentence outcomes that were rehabilitative of the offender, protective of the victim and the community, and which drew on the authority of the court. Least favoured was the imposition of a fine or for the violent person to perform a service for the victim. Then, when asked to specify their first and second priority out of these sentence preferences, women’s views sharpened. Of primary importance was that the violent person had some type of treatment: for drugs and alcohol, violence rehabilitation or mental health. Next was to have a custodial sentence of some type imposed: weekend detention, a suspended sentence or full-time custody. Finally, the women were asked to indicate which justice principle out of nine choices they would like a magistrate or judge to apply to their case. Their answers clustered strongly on the principle of rehabilitation (76% said it was of ‘utmost importance’), and then on principles of 15 victim protection and specific deterrence of the offender. While 29% of women said the principle of restorative justice was of ‘utmost importance’, most rejected the option of apology, whether made in person or in writing. More women (48%) thought that an apology was ‘undesirable and would make matters worse’ than those who thought it was essential (19%). In giving reasons for their preferences, women joined their thinking to the justice trilogy of victim, offender and their community of others. Their comments reiterated a desire for accountability and for recognition of the wrongfulness of the perpetrator’s behaviour, and unfolded in two ways. Polly’s comments are illustrative. First and for herself, Polly wanted to be safe—a self-regarding objective. Then, she went on to emphasize what ‘he’ needs and her goal for other ‘human beings’—the two other objects in the justice trilogy. She said, He definitely needs to be taught that it is absolutely wrong to hurt another human being. When he has paid his price, then there needs to be something in place so he never does it again; and there needs to be things available to help him and to help him be a better person. [Emphasis added] Polly also emphasized different consequences to the perpetrator for the violent behaviour. Her reasons combined concepts of censure (taught that it is absolutely wrong), punishment (paying a price), deterrence (he never does it again), and rehabilitation (things to help him). Nearly all women in the study voiced their multiple justice goals in this manner: specifying the object and giving the reason. Their goals were multi-directional, and their reasoning reflected different dimensions to justice. Polly’s comments above also reveal an ordering of her multiple goals. They are sequenced in that one follows the other: first censure, then punishment, then deterrence and then rehabilitation. 16 Prospective process preferences At Time 1, women were also asked through what criminal justice steps they could envisage achieving their multiple goals. They were provided with eight possible resolution pathways (in both visual and written format and as shown in Table 1) to a justice process that lay ahead of them. Different types of participatory activity in the pathways included giving a victim impact statement (VIS) and being part of a restorative opportunity.14 The latter was described as an occasion, with a trained facilitator, to discuss with the violent person what happened and what should happen next. Two groups emerged in the analysis. Four women (19%) preferred an informal justice process. They wanted the violent person to make an admission to the police, but then wished to see the case diverted from the criminal court process. They did not indicate an interest in the court making a guilty finding. These women wanted their relationship with the violent person to continue, and the reasons they gave for diversion focused on relationship repair. However, at times, their preference was qualified: ‘if he hadn’t hit rock bottom and bounced back, I might have a different opinion’, one said. A second group of 17 women (81%) preferred a formal justice process. Their first preference was for the case to be decided in court with a guilty finding. In this group, one woman wanted her relationship with the violent person to continue, five were unsure or thought ‘maybe not’, and 10 ‘definitely’ did not want the relationship to continue. After a court finding, this group split into two sub-groups with respect to pathways. One quarter wanted no or minimal participation by them as victim. They wanted the system to ‘deal with it’ or felt that more involvement from them would ‘make matters worse’. However, most wanted some participatory involvement, identifying varied sequence configurations. 17 TABLE 1: Women’s preferred justice process, n=21 at the Time 1 interview Process options Number In fo rm al ju st ic e pr ef er en ce s Diversion (19%, n=4) Admission, divert and mediate 3 Admission, restorative opportunity, no formal sentence 1 Fo rm al ju st ic e pr ef er en ce s No/minimal participation (24%, n=5) Finding and sentence 5 Participation, no restorative opportunity (24%, n=5) Finding, victim impact statement (VIS) and sentence 5 Participation and restorative opportunities (33%, n=7) Finding, restorative opportunity, no sentence 0 Finding, restorative opportunity, court hears agreement, sentence 3 Finding, sentence, restorative opportunity 1 Finding, VIS, sentence, restorative opportunity 3 18 The court’s guilty finding was an essential first step for those in the formal justice preference group. Women said that this decision made the perpetrator’s culpability clear. They also felt that, after this occurred, they as victims could then deliver information to the court about what to do next and the offender may be more strongly influenced by the court’s sentencing decision. Quinn, for example, said, ‘the fact that I don’t have to be around him and that it’s done by someone who is seen to be “the law” so it sends the message to him that what he’s done is not acceptable’. Eight of those who preferred a formal process felt it was also important for the court and the violent person to hear about the impact of the offence on them through a VIS. Janelle said this was ‘because I can tell him what [the abuse] has done and how it has made me feel. I couldn’t face him without being in the court because we’d just yell at each other’. However, reflection on the possibility of a VIS was not simply about conveying the harm done. Nada, for example, said that the Magistrate really needs to hear from the victim to make a proper decision. There is a lot lost between what happens and reading something off a paper. If they can read a VIS and ask questions, it would be good. They need to hear the whole history. The women viewed the VIS as being potentially influential on the decision-maker. Alice said, ‘I think what level of impact it [the offence] has made on my life now and at the time should be dealt with accordingly, which should aid their sentence’. Comments such as these show that the women wanted to see dialogue as not only flowing between victim and offender, but also triangulating with an authoritative decision-maker. 19 Seven women in the formal justice group preferred a participatory mix, including a restorative opportunity, after the authoritative finding. The reasons for this configuration tended to combine concerns for the violent person as well as for themselves. Karla, for example, said the following: [My ex-partner’s] actively taking responsibility for his actions and being part of deciding what should happen in front of me would be quite healing for me. At the moment he has nothing but hatred and blame for me and I’d like that responsibility to shift. The feeling of his consent to the sentence feels important. The judge can impose it but he can still not own it. Karla’s comment shows an interaction between her private (interpersonal) interests and her desire to see these ratified in a public forum or by a public authority—what we term her public interests. She wanted her ex-partner to face her and take responsibility for his behaviour in private, and at the same time, she believed that his accepting responsibility would deepen when he was sentenced for the wrongful behaviour in the public forum of the court. Preferences for a process that combined private interests and public authority often came in a flow of reasoning. Olivia described achieving her goals as stepping one to the other by using the terms ‘and’, ‘also’, and ‘and then’. In response to the question, ‘What is it about these particular [resolution] processes or steps that is most attractive to you?’, she said: He’s been found guilty and then the chance to come together to talk about the impacts on me, but also to work together about how to make things different in the future. Also for me to highlight the services that could help. These could be agreed and then come back to the court. Both [of us are] able to be heard and be heard at the sentence where our ideas are taken into account at sentence. Both [of us] have a chance to influence the 20 sentence. But if you can’t, then the judge would make the final sentence. [Emphasis added] Here plainly we see the language of sequence. Not long after the actual incident and looking ahead, the women at Time 1 envisaged their multiple goals for justice beginning first with an accountability threshold and then moving through varied process steps. Time 2: After Prosecution and Court Thus far, we have presented women’s prospective thinking, that is, what they wanted from decision-makers in the future and through what decision-making pathway. What did they think at their second interview after the case had finished? On this occasion, which was between two to four weeks after the court case finished, women were asked what they had wanted from the prosecutor and from the court, and their perspective on the decisions actually made, that is, their retrospective reflections. Retrospective reflections on justice goals At Time 2, two more women indicated that they had asked for the charges to be dropped, raising the number from five to seven. The reasons the seven women gave were varied. Three had reconciled or were concerned about the possibility of a gaol sentence, and two mentioned the length of time involved in the process. A further two discussed direct pressures placed on them. Polly, for example, had her tyres slashed after the police charged her ex-partner with assaulting her. She also said, ‘I definitely didn’t want to testify. I was frightened what would happen from people he knows. I thought there’d be retaliation. I didn’t think the system would protect me’. When asked what they had ‘mainly’ wanted the prosecutor to do, 16 (76%) indicated preferences for prosecuting all or some of the charges.15 The women repeated strongly their 21 concern for accountability as a primary driver. For example, when explaining why she wanted the charges to proceed, Karla said, ‘because he did the action and if he suffered the consequences, maybe he won’t do it again. It was a serious thing he did’. The women gave similar reasons for the case proceeding as they did in their first interview: they wanted acknowledgement for themselves, some meaningful consequence for the violent person, and protection for others. Then, asked whether they remained in favour or against the court finding the violent person guilty or not guilty, 18 women (two more than at Time 1) preferred a guilty finding. For the two who changed their minds, both had wanted the relationship to continue at Time 1 and still did so at Time 2. Asked why she now preferred the guilty finding, Aimee said ‘because he was guilty. He accepts that’. Roslyn now wanted her partner ‘to be accountable for what he did because I [don’t] want to be afraid in my own home. If I’m not true to myself, if I give up on my strong sense, then that’s not good. It’s being true to my values’. These comments give a sense of the weight that the public authority of criminal justice loaned the women. At this point in the study, all but two cases had been resolved by way of a guilty plea (91%). If outcome favourability is, in part, ‘personally beneficial’, in that a personal goal(s) is achieved (Krehbiel and Cropanzano 2000: 340–341), then, given their desire for offender accountability, the women were vindicated by the offender’s guilty plea and the court’s finding. In addition, they continued to prefer treatment-oriented court outcomes from the first to the second interview. The reasons they gave were overwhelmingly offender-focused, citing the need for measures to stop the violence, to change other harmful behaviours, and for the offender to realize the wrongfulness of his conduct. The actual sentence was known at this stage, with most men sentenced to court orders or bonds ‘to be of good behaviour’ (N=13) with eight of these 22 additionally subject to probation supervision. Next in frequency was some form of custody (actual, deferred or suspended, N=5). For the remaining three, one received community service and two cases received some treatment (violence rehabilitation or drug/alcohol programs) as part of the sentence. Thus, most women received the desired guilty finding but not their preferred sentence. As an example, Teresa said at Time 1 that she preferred the court to sentence her ex- partner with a violence rehabilitation order and an order to keep away from her. However, he received a 12-month bond to be of good behaviour and no probation supervision. Reflecting on the court outcomes at her second interview, Teresa said that she ‘wasn’t sure what to expect, but I just wanted him to understand and get the message from the highest authority that what he was doing was wrong, that he had to stop’. The blend of both personal interests (that he ‘understand’) and the call to ‘the highest’ public authority is evident in her comment. Retrospective reflection on participatory opportunities At this second interview, conducted just after the court case had concluded, the women were asked if they would have liked a ‘restorative opportunity’ had it been offered. Compared to the first interview in which eight said they would have taken the opportunity, more said they would do so at Time 2 (N=13, 62%): eight said ‘definitely’ they would have, and five said ‘maybe’. Four (19%) were unsure, and four would not have done so. Of the 13 who said they would or might have taken up this opportunity, most did not want to continue the relationship with the man. Analysing the 13 women further, seven said that they would have preferred a restorative opportunity before a finding. Of this group, three had expressed a preference for diversion at the first interview. As one of these, Yvette explained that ‘it would make a better understanding for all involved and it might give another idea other than prosecuting—maybe counselling’. Six saw 23 the restorative opportunity coming after the finding, or what Miller and Iovanni (2012: 24) term a ‘postconviction dialogue’. Holly had not wanted any restorative opportunity at her first interview. She now thought she was ‘safer’ for a dialogue to be offered after the court finding, after her ex-partner’s violent behaviour was constrained and within the confines of public authority. In describing the potential of a restorative opportunity, the 13 women often spoke of their desire to convey something to the violent person. This included a discussion of the harm to them, the consequences to others, the wrongfulness of the assault, and the desire for a different person or different relationship. None mentioned an apology. Genevieve said she would ‘have liked to have gotten him to admit what he was doing was wrong or to see if he could even admit this’. Imogene thought a restorative opportunity could enable her ‘to say “ok this is what you did and these are the consequences to me and your son” and to try to get him to understand that there are consequences to others’. In general, the women with some interest in a restorative opportunity saw the potential of the meeting to contribute to the offender’s accepting responsibility for his behaviour and its consequences to him and to her as a victim. For a few women, the potential of a restorative opportunity was to get some answers. Xenia had ‘niggling questions unanswered’. Roslyn, Teresa and Polly ‘wanted to know why’. Polly said, ‘it ate away [at me]. It was really because it was just so aggressive.’ For the eight women who were unsure or not interested in a restorative opportunity, half did not want the relationship with the violent person to continue and half were unsure. These women generally wished to keep or extend the distance between themselves and the violent person. Nada said, ‘I think I needed to be as removed as possible from the situation. He was in such a bad state that anything I would have done would have inflamed [him]’. For some, concern 24 about their safety underlay their caution about a possible restorative interaction. For example, Winona said she wasn’t sure ‘because I don’t really have anything to say to him and maybe I’d be a bit scared he would lash out at me again’. Others commented that the violent person would not have been genuine in a restorative interaction or would have been manipulative, blaming or threatening. Lorraine was unsure about a restorative opportunity. Talking about her ex-partner, she said, ‘he’s very good at putting on a front, especially when it comes to guilt. He’s a very good actor’. Birgit felt ‘it wouldn’t have made any difference. We spoke on the phone, and he was blaming me for [his] being in [custody]. Even after three weeks he was blaming me. He’s just got to take responsibility’. Thus, compared to those who saw potential for a restorative opportunity with an offender, the eight who were unsure or saw no potential were sizing up concerns for their own safety and the men’s readiness to engage in the process in a constructive and respectful manner, and his readiness to accept responsibility. Time 3: Six Months after the Court Case Finished The Time 3 interviews were conducted six to eight months after the case had finished at court. Recall that compared to the 21 women interviewed twice, the 14 interviewed at Time 3 were of somewhat higher socio-economic status, more likely to have been in a shorter-term relationship with the assailant, and increasingly composed of those who had called the police themselves, but did not want the man arrested. Only two of those who had initially preferred an informal justice process remained at Time 3. Despite sample attrition, the benefits of understanding the views of those at Time 3 outweigh the drawbacks. Specifically, they provide a longer-term reflection of the women’s experiences with the criminal justice process and what, if any, subsequent violence had occurred. 25 When asked if they had felt involved enough with their case during the criminal justice process: 50% said they were, 29% said that they were not and 21% were unsure. The women were also asked about the ‘outcome decisions’ made by ‘the justice system’; that is, they were asked to give a global reflection about all the decisions not just the sentence, and about the system as a whole and not any specific part. Most (64%) agreed the decisions reached had been fair. Their answers to other items were more ambivalent. When asked if the decisions were ‘deserved’ by them as a victim, a third each said yes, no or unsure; and equal proportions agreed (43%) and disagreed (43%) that the justice system decisions were what they ‘wanted’. These are not overwhelmingly positive evaluations of criminal justice. Nonetheless, the women’s original motivation in calling for police assistance was largely achieved: 57% said there had been no further violence since the case was finalized in court. Over two thirds (79%) said they felt safe, and 64% agreed with the statement that ‘justice system intervention has had an impact in stopping the violence against me’. However, when asked if they felt that justice had been done, 57% agreed. Like their views in Time 2, their reflections on the nature of justice done tended to focus on the offender and how the justice responses did or did not facilitate accountability and change. Repeated in many women’s comments (with emphases added here) were hopes for the offender to think about what he had done and to realize a different way to be. Birgit’s ex-partner had received eight months’ gaol time although she had preferred treatment for his alcohol use. Even so, of his time in gaol, she hoped ‘he's had time to think and realize that his behaviour has to stop’. Janelle had preferred a custodial sentence for her ex-partner although this did not occur. She wanted it to have been ‘long enough for him to realize he did wrong’. She went on to say ‘when you're on a 26 good behaviour bond, you live your life normally. When you are in gaol, you have to sit and think about what you've done’. Not only did the women want the offender to think about and acknowledge the wrongfulness of the behaviour, they wanted that realization to turn outwards to others. As an example, Finoula had separated from her ex-partner, but she hoped that the conviction had ‘planted a seed in his mind not to do this to anyone else’. Holly’s ex-partner had been convicted and received a deferred sentence. She did not think that justice had been done in her case, and she referred to herself and her daughter in explaining why. She said, ‘justice would be him in a rehab and not being able to contact us’. Svetlana drew on wider community debate to say that ‘if the government is on such a stance about violence against women, [my ex] should have gotten some more. It wasn’t his first time and it [the sentence] needs to get harder as it goes along’. Others were less certain about having achieved victim-related justice goals. Half of the women disagreed with a statement that ‘my interests as a victim of violence were looked after by the justice system’. Ursula had successfully petitioned the prosecution not to proceed with the charges against her husband. Ultimately, however, she came to regret this decision and to believe that justice had not been done. While she remained married and living with him, she observed that ‘he got the outcome for him, but I haven’t. I’m no safer than I was then’. The period of time that had elapsed from the original incident and the Time 3 interview (about a year) had enabled her to speak more directly to her own interests. She said she would have liked to be able to say to her husband, if he had threatened her again, ‘don’t forget there’s an order [of the court]’. Olivia didn’t ‘feel any safer’ despite her ex-partner’s conviction. She still slept ‘with the phone and keys and with the door locked’. She had wanted ‘help’ for her ex-partner but did not feel that she ‘as an individual matter[ed]’. She went on to say that ‘victims need to know more and to know 27 why. They need better explanations … a very strong support network including information about the court system’. On the other hand, Aimee agreed that justice had been done, but at the same time noted the difficulties she faced as a victim in the process. She said her partner ‘was made to realize the seriousness of his actions’ and that the criminal justice consequences ‘all had a deep and lasting impact on him’. But, she wryly observed, ‘you’re just dragged along in all this’. These comments reveal a vulnerability felt by victims that is more diffuse than that experienced solely in relation to the offender. Ursula’s remark that she ‘needed someone just for me [in the justice process]’ recognized her aloneness and irrelevance in a system not designed with victims’ interests in mind. ‘They all listen, but you are no further ahead’, she said. Discussion Previous research suggests that between 21% to 35% of women who experience physical violence from a partner or ex-partner seek the intervention of criminal justice authorities (Cox 2016; Felson et al 2005; Johnson 2006; Walby and Allen 2004). The women in this study did so because they wanted an end to the violence, and they drew on the authority of the police and courts to help reach this goal. Most achieved this goal and felt safer. However, this was not their only objective. Their claims for justice related to their connection with the violent person and their sense of obligation to others, in addition to themselves as victims. It was for this trilogy of interests that women sought justice. In their view, justice was due to all (Swift 2014). For most women, justice entailed both procedural and substantive elements. Their reasoning for pursuing justice was instrumental (that is, to stop the violence or change the offending behaviour) and ethical (that is, to protect others or reinforce desirable community values). It interwove private and public interests. The women were nearly unanimous in naming 28 accountability of the offender (private interest) as a motivation for mobilizing the law, and that the law hold him to account (public interest).16 Not long after police attended the incident and before the case had reached court, most women further sought accountability through a guilty finding and composite sentences that addressed their different goals. While the incident had emotional impacts, only one of the 21 women mentioned ‘healing’ as an objective and none spontaneously mentioned an interest in the offender’s apologising to them. Asked prospectively before the case went to court, a high share of women said that they preferred to reach their goals in a process that relied on the court’s guilty finding and then they would consider other participatory steps such as a VIS or a restorative opportunity. It was after guilt had been established, and thus in the shadow of the court’s conviction, that more women at their second interview indicated a retrospective willingness to consider a restorative opportunity. They saw it as an occasion for the violent person to ‘realize’ what he had done, its effects and its wrongfulness. Over time, the women were consistent in seeking a conviction and consistent in other sub-goals of rehabilitation, victim protection, and drawing on the authority of the court to deter future offending. These rested on women’s view that the behaviour was wrong, that the violent person was culpable, and that the intention behind the behaviour needed to be stopped. The language women used and the reasons they gave for the justice they desired did not so much change as unfold and deepen over the course of three interviews. Making sense of justice and sequencing It is this process of unfolding and deepening that a prospective longitudinal methodology can reveal. Research on what ‘justice’ women claim after domestic violence is often divided into opposing or entirely separate options. These are then studied at a single point in time, commonly 29 retrospectively. Such approaches have obscured the fact that victims have varied preferences and concerns, described by Gromet and Darley as ‘justice goals’, towards the ‘ultimate goal of achieving justice’ (2009: 2). The authors argue that a process of ‘controlled reasoning’ can generate consideration of multiple goals and multiple targets of those goals (2009: 29). Women’s goals and targets were revealed when they were provided with more than one opportunity to speak about their case over time. They spoke expansively by depicting a conception of justice that was layered and multi-directional. What may initially seem to be contradictory or even changeable thinking is instead sequenced thinking about different targets of an overarching goal of justice, and of the interests with which they are concerned: self, offender, others. Taken together, these interests, sub-goals and reasons constitute what Sen calls ‘plural grounding’ for justice (2009: 2). Moreover, interviewing women at the different focal points of police, prosecution and court finalization showed the contingency embedded within their judgements about justice (Skitka et al. 2010). Sub-goals for justice, from the court’s guilty finding to various combinations of sentence, are articulated one after the other as a sequence, and may be reached in a sequence. Thus, for example, the court’s guilty finding was a crucial marker of accountability that was distinct from sanctions that came with sentencing. Accountability is both a threshold goal and a reference point in the justice process. Moreover, our study shows that the process creates a kind of sequenced architecture in which justice and its sub-goals may be progressively articulated by women and progressively achieved. These spaces and opportunities create the possibility for what Stubbs (2012) has called ‘a hybrid approach’ to justice for victims of domestic violence. Whereas she emphasises the ‘conditions’ needed for restorative justice to be ‘safe and effective’ for gendered violence (2012: 213), we emphasise hybridity of 30 conventional and innovative processes in which women may be involved. Contemporary criminal justice remains antithetical to this degree of victim participation and articulation. Yet women’s interest in participating in different ways and at different occasions with different intents was precisely because a publicly sanctioned criminal justice system had the authority and means to facilitate and deliver (if only incompletely) their multiple goals. If we use the idea of ‘the sequencing of justice goals’, we are able to see that one set of justice principles or terms need not be privileged over another, nor that one must happen before the other. Elsewhere, one of us has observed that the youth justice conferencing process can permit time for participants to express multiple justice principles, not just one. As a consequence, ‘retributive, restorative, and rehabilitative principles and terms are intermingled, or they may shift in emphasis, depending on the conference phase’ (Daly 2000). Our study shows the same for victims of domestic violence in a conventional criminal justice process. Here, however, the time frame is not a 60-minute conference, but a substantially longer time and multiple occasions as a case moves through a criminal process and six to eight months after it concludes. By taking this longer view, we are able to see the idea of justice from a victim’s perspective as a sequenced activity comprising distinct layers, not as it is often portrayed, as a oppositional dichotomy. ‘Repair or revenge’ (Strang 2002), ‘restorative or retributive’ (Zehr 1990), rehabilitation or punishment, among other examples, have promulgated a misleading and distorted understanding of the justice many victims, including those affected by domestic violence, seek in the aftermath of crime. 31 References BARATA, P. (2007), ‘Abused Women’s Perspectives on the Criminal Justice System’s Response to Domestic Violence’, Psychology of Women Quarterly, 31/2: 202-215. BELL, N., PEREZ, S., GOODMAN, L. and DUTTON, M. (2011), ‘Battered Women’s Perceptions of Civil and Criminal Court Helpfulness: The Role of Court Outcome and Process’, Violence Against Women, 17/1: 71-88. BOYKIN, D., LONDON, M. and ORCUTT, H. (2016), ‘Examining Minority Attrition Among Women in Longitudinal Trauma Research’, Journal of Traumatic Stress, 29: 26-32. CHRISTIE, N. (1977), ‘Conflicts as Property’, The British Journal of Criminology, 17/1: 1-15. COX, P. (2016), Violence Against Women: Additional Analysis of the Australian Bureau of Statistics' Personal Safety Survey, 2012, ANROWS Horizons: 01.01/2016 Rev. ed. Sydney: ANROWS. DALY, K. (2000), ‘Revisiting the Relationship between Retributive and Restorative Justice’. In H. Strang and J. Braithwaite eds, Restorative Justice: From Philosophy to Practice, 33-54. Ashgate. DALY, K. and STUBBS, J. (2006), ‘Feminist Engagement with Restorative Justice’, Theoretical Criminology, Special Issue on Gender, Race, and Restorative Justice, 10/1: 9-28. DOBASH, R. E. and DOBASH, R.P. (1992), Women, Violence and Social Change. Routledge. EREZ, E. and BELKNAP, J. (1998), ‘In Their Own Words: Battered Women's Assessment of the Criminal Processing System's Responses’, Violence and Victims, 13/3: 251-268. FELSON, R., ACKERMAN, J. and GALLAGHER, C. (2005), ‘Police Intervention and the Repeat of Domestic Assault’, Criminology, 43/3: 563-588. 32 FLEURY, R. (2002), ‘Missing Voices: Patterns of Battered Women’s Satisfaction with the Criminal Justice System’, Violence Against Women, 8/2: 181-205. FLEURY-STEINER, R., BYBEE, D., SULLIVAN, C., BELKNAP, J. and MELTON, H. (2006), ‘Contextual Factors Impacting Battered Women’s Intentions to Reuse the Criminal Legal System’, Journal of Community Psychology, 34/3: 327-342. FORD, D. (1991). ‘Prosecution as a Victim Power Resource: A Note on Empowering Women in Violent Conjugal Relationships’, Law and Society Review, 25/2: 313-334. GROMET, D. and DARLEY, J. (2009), ‘Punishment and Beyond: Achieving Justice Through the Satisfaction of Multiple Goals’, Law and Society Review, 43/1: 1-38. HARE, S. (2006), ‘What do Battered Women Want? Victims’ Opinions on Prosecution’, Violence and Victims, 21/5: 611-628. HERMAN, J. (2005), ‘Justice from The Victim’s Perspective’, Violence Against Women, 11/5: 571-602. HIRSCHEL, D. and HUTCHISON, I. (2003), ‘The Voices of Domestic Violence Victims: Predictors of Victim Preference for Arrest and the Relationship Between Preference for Arrest and Re-Victimization’, Crime & Delinquency, 49/2: 313-336. HOLDER, R. (2007), ‘Police and Domestic Violence: An Analysis of Domestic Violence Incidents Attended By Police in the ACT and Subsequent Actions’, Research Paper 4, August. Sydney: Australian Domestic and Family Violence Clearinghouse. HOLDER, R. (2013/2018), Just Interests: Victims, Citizens and the Potential for Justice. PhD thesis. Canberra: The Australian National University. Revised for 2018 publication by Edward Elgar. 33 HOLDER, R. (2015), ‘Satisfied? Exploring Victims’ Justice Judgements’. In D. Wilson and S. Ross eds, Crime, Victims and Policy: International Contexts, Local Experiences, 184-213. Palgrave. HOLDER, R. (2016), ‘Untangling the Meanings of Justice: A Longitudinal Mixed Methods Study’, Journal of Mixed Methods Research, Online version, 1-17, DOI: 10.1177/1558689816653308 HOLDER, R. and CARUANA, J. (2006), Criminal Justice Intervention in Family Violence in the ACT, November. Canberra: Victims of Crime Coordinator. HOYLE, C. and SANDERS, A. (2000), ‘Police Response to Domestic Violence: From Victim Choice to Victim Empowerment’, British Journal of Criminology, 40: 14-36. JOHNSON, H. (2006). Measuring Violence Against Women: Statistical Trends 2006. Ottawa: Minister of Industry. KREHBIEL, P. and CROPANZANO, R. (2000), ‘Procedural Justice, Outcome Favourability and Emotion’, Social Justice Research, 13/4: 339-360. LEWIS, R., DOBASH, R. P., DOBASH, R. E., and CAVANAGH, K. (2000), ‘Protection, Prevention, Rehabilitation or Justice? Women's Use of the Law to Challenge Domestic Violence’, International Review of Victimology, 7/1-3: 179-205. MCFARLANE, J., WILLSON, P., LEMMEY, D. & MALECHA, A. (2000), ‘Women Filing Assault Charges on an Intimate Partner’, Violence Against Women, 6/4: 396-408. McGILLIVRAY, A. and COMASKEY, B. (1999), Black Eyes All of the Time: Intimate Violence, Aboriginal Women, And the Justice System. University of Toronto Press. 34 MILLER, S. and IOVANNI, L. (2013), ‘Using Restorative Justice for Gendered Violence: Success with a Postconviction Model’, Feminist Criminology, 20/10: 1-22. MILLS, L. (1999), ‘Killing Her Softly: Intimate Abuse and the Violence of State Intervention’, Harvard Law Review, 113/2: 550-613. MINAKER, J. (2001), ‘Evaluating Criminal Justice Responses to Intimate Abuse Through the Lens of Women’s Needs’, Canadian Journal of Women and the Law, 13: 74-106. NANCARROW, H. (2006), ‘In Search Of Justice for Domestic and Family Violence: Indigenous and Non-Indigenous Australian Women’s Perspectives’, Theoretical Criminology, 10/1: 87- 106. NOVISKY, M. and PERALTA, R. (2015), ‘When Women Tell: Intimate Partner Violence and the Factors Related to Police Notification’, Violence Against Women, 21/1: 65-86. PLANO CLARK, V., ANDERSON, N., WERTZ, J., ZHOU, Y., SCHUMACHER, K. and MIASKOWSKI, C. (2014), ‘Conceptualizing Longitudinal Mixed Methods Designs: a Methodological Review of Health Sciences Research’, Journal of Mixed Methods Research, Online version, 1-23, DOI: 10.1177/1558689814543563 RUBIN, P. (2010), ‘A Community of One’s Own? When Women Speak to Power About Restorative Justice’. In J. Ptacek, ed, Restorative Justice and Violence Against Women, 79- 104. Oxford University Press. SEN, A. (2009), The Idea of Justice, The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. SKITKA, L., ARAMOVICH, N., LYTLE, B. and SARGIS, E. (2010), ‘Knitting Together an Elephant: An Integrative Approach to Understanding the Psychology of Justice Reasoning’. 35 In R. Bobocel, A. Kay, M. Zanna, and J. Olson, eds, The Psychology of Justice and Legitimacy: The Ontario Symposium (Volume 11), 1-26. Psychology Press. SMITH, A. (2001), ‘Domestic Violence Laws: The Voices of Battered Women’, Violence and Victims, 16/1: 91-111. SNIDER, L. (1998), ‘Towards Safer Societies: Punishment, Masculinities and Violence Against Women’, British Journal of Criminology, 38/1: 1-39. STRANG, H. (2002), Repair or Revenge: Victims and Restorative Justice. Clarendon Press. STUBBS, J. (2012), ‘Justice for Gendered Violence: What does Restorative Justice Offer?' In J. Bolitho, J. Bruce and G. Mason, eds, Restorative Justice: Adults and Emerging Practice, 194-213. Sydney Institute of Criminology. SWIFT, A. (2014), Political Philosophy: A Beginners’ Guide for Students and Politicians, 2nd edition, Polity Press. VAN CAMP, T. and WEMMERS, J. (2013), ‘Victim Satisfaction with Restorative Justice More than Simply Procedural Justice’, International Review of Victimology, 19/2: 117-143. VISHER, C., HARRELL, A., NEWMARK, L. and YAHNER, J. (2008), ‘Reducing Intimate Partner Violence: An Evaluation of a Comprehensive Justice System-Community Collaboration’, Criminology and Public Policy, 7/4: 495-523. WALBY, S. and ALLEN, J. (2004), Domestic Violence, Sexual Assault and Stalking: Findings from the British Crime Survey, Home Office Research Study 276, Home Office. WEMMERS, J. (2008), ‘Victim Participation and Therapeutic Jurisprudence’, Victims and Offenders, 3/2-3: 165-191. 36 WESTMARLAND, N., JOHNSON, K. and McGLYNN, C. (2017), ‘Under the Radar: The Widespread Use of “Out Of Court Resolutions” in Policing Domestic Violence and Abuse in the United Kingdom’, British Journal of Criminology, 1-16, doi:10.1093/bjc/azx004 YOUNG, A., POWERS, J. and BELL, S. (2006), ‘Attrition in Longitudinal Studies: Who Do You Lose?’, Australian and New Zealand Journal of Public Health, 30/4: 353-361. ZEHR, H. (1990), Changing Lenses: A New Focus for Criminal Justice. Herald Press. 37 1 In this study, domestic violence is defined as intimate partner violence, in which a woman was victimised by a male partner or ex-partner. 2 McFarlane et al. (2000) interviewed women at Time 1 when they intended to file assault charges. The article discusses retrospective findings at Time 2. 3 Ford (1991) used a limited prospective design in a study of 25 women who initially sought prosecution; he subsequently interviewed 13 to determine why they had ‘dropped charges’ before the case went to court. 4 The average time for each interview at all three interview points was 65 minutes. 5 From 1994 to 2011, the first author worked as a statutory victim advocate in the study jurisdiction and led a coordinated community and criminal justice response to domestic violence (Holder and Caruana 2006). 6 With small sample sizes and non-independent samples, we did not carry out tests of statistical significance, but instead identified when differences were 10 percentage points or greater on the variables. 7 They were also more likely to speak another language at home in addition to English, a measure often associated with increased attrition of ‘minorities’ (Boykin et al. 2016). For this sample, however, bilingualism was associated with having a tertiary education. 8 One woman earned between $100,000 and $250,000. The 2011 average gross individual income of a full-time employee in Australia was $53,000 (approximately GBP 34,000 or USD 54,000, using the 2011 average exchange rate). 9 In these two cases the prosecution had offered no evidence and the charges were dismissed in court. For both, the women made strong representations to prosecution to drop the charges: one 38 because she believed her husband was mentally unwell and the other because of particular circumstances that led to the violence. 10 Sixteen (76%) of those interviewed twice said that they had initiated the call to police themselves. Of the five who did not, two said that they supported the report being made, two were unsure and one did not want the report made. 11 All names used are pseudonyms. 12 Although 14 of the 21 women had children living with them at the time of the incident, just four of the 14 (29%) mentioned children in their reasons for calling the police. 13 Gromet and Darley call these three ‘justice targets’ (2006: 2). 14 In the study jurisdiction, there were a number of legislated paths for the resolution of a criminal offence. At the time of the study, one of these was a restorative conference for youth matters (if the alleged offender made an admission or was convicted) but not for adults and not for domestic violence. Despite this, pre-admission or conviction options for a restorative encounter were put to the study participants. They were advised that these options were not actually available to them and that they were being asked in order to gain some idea of the degree of interest. 15 There is a surface inconsistency between seven women saying they had asked for charges to be dropped and 16 saying they wanted all or some of the charges prosecuted. However, the first is a response to an open question about an action undertaken ‘at any time’ during the prosecution process. The second derives from closed response options that focused narrowly on ‘when the prosecution was dealing with your case’. 16 Public interest is defined as that which is of common concern to the general populace. It is often separated from a private interest. Women’s comments showed private and public interest as 39 interweaving and mutually defining. The example of offender accountability shows private interest for it and public interest that it is secured as being two sides of the same coin. Likewise, for individuals to live free of violence is an objective that is a private and a public interest. SEQUENCING JUSTICE: A LONGITUDINAL STUDY OF JUSTICE GOALS OF DOMESTIC VIOLENCE VICTIMS SEQUENCING JUSTICE: A LONGITUDINAL STUDY OF JUSTICE GOALS OF DOMESTIC VIOLENCE VICTIMS SEQUENCING JUSTICE: A LONGITUDINAL STUDY OF JUSTICE GOALS OF DOMESTIC VIOLENCE VICTIMS SEQUENCING JUSTICE: A LONGITUDINAL STUDY OF JUSTICE GOALS OF DOMESTIC VIOLENCE VICTIMS Women, violence and justice A longitudinal prospective study Time 1: Police Intervention Prospective process preferences Time 2: After Prosecution and Court Time 3: Six Months after the Court Case Finished Discussion Making sense of justice and sequencing References work_7t5kp5jyybaqvkadiouxxmoxsa ---- Virtual Mentor Virtual Mentor American Medical Association Journal of Ethics July 2011, Volume 13, Number 7: 448-453. CONLEY ESSAY CONTEST 2010 Winning Essay Social (Networking) Justice Russell J. Coletti Emily, a medical school candidate, had high grades and MCAT scores and extensive volunteer experience. The committee members who interviewed her reported that Emily had spoken movingly about her desire to become a primary care physician in a rural setting. The committee’s student member, Jason, looked up Emily on Facebook to see whether they had any friends in common. There he found a link to a blog post that attributed rising rates of contagious disease and unemployment to illegal immigrants. Emily had added: “I couldn’t agree more. People whose mothers just happened to sneak over the border at the right time are called ‘citizens’ when they’re just driving down wages, straining our infrastructure, and taking jobs that rightly belong to honest, hardworking taxpayers. Why should we take care of them?” Emily’s Facebook post revealed a side of her that Jason knew the admissions committee hadn’t seen, and he wondered what he should do with this information. Response Just when access to information at a moment’s notice seems like old news, a growing trend in the virtual world is the ability to share personal experiences and ideas with one’s friends and family anywhere. Social networking sites like Facebook and Twitter have allowed insight into an individual’s life like never before, but in what situations is such insight appropriate? In the case of medical school hopeful Emily, online social networking activities should not be considered during the selection process for her admittance. In order to narrow the applicant pool, medical schools have adopted a three-stage process: screening, interviewing, and selection [1]. Because there are a limited number of positions in the entering class, it can be said that admission represents a limited good to be disbursed at the admission committee’s will. Given this arrangement, one can see that justice becomes an important part of the selection process. In his book Beginning Bioethics, Aaron Ridley defines justice as “giving people what is fair, due, or owed to them” [2], in other words giving people what they deserve. Applying this idea to the admissions process, if the committee determines that an applicant deserves admission, then the committee ought to grant it. The information the committee uses to determine whether the applicant’s academic achievements and character are deserving of admission is that which the Virtual Mentor, July 2011—Vol 13 www.virtualmentor.org 448 applicant submits in the first two stages of the process: screening and interviewing. The end of the interview stage marks the point in the process after which the applicant cannot defend, expand upon, or put into context any information that the committee considers. Equally important is the fact that the applicant has only knowingly submitted information up to that point and has thus been in control of its content. This is not unlike a trial proceeding, in which a jury (analogous to the admission committee) decides on a defendant’s deservingness of acquittal (or conviction) based upon information presented during the case. In this arena where, ideally, justice is preserved, the jury is only to consider the information presented formally in court, where the defendant has the opportunity to counter or defend the information presented. Indeed there have been cases in which jurors have used social networking sites, among other Internet resources, to convey or discover information not deemed admissible by the judge, which resulted in mistrials. For instance, in a Florida case where the defendant was accused of selling prescription drugs illegally over the Internet, 8 weeks of proceedings unraveled into a mistrial when several of the jurors conducted online research about the case [3]. Clearly, consulting resources beyond the confines of the proper pathways has been deemed unfair in the legal system, as the information no longer can be properly scrutinized, particularly by the party to whom the information pertains. Proper, fair pathways also exist in the selection process for medical school. According to the Liaison Committee on Medical Education, which sets accreditation standards for all U.S. medical schools, an institution “must develop criteria, policies, and procedures for selection…that are readily available to…applicants” [4]. Furthermore, the Association of American Medical Colleges dictates that an institution develop “clear, consistent criteria and processes” [1] for selection. Thus, a just process guarantees the applicants both transparency and consistency in the admission guidelines. Indeed there are now actually two criteria for justice within the selection process: (i) that those to whom admission is due ultimately receive it, and (ii) that all applicants receive what they are owed from the onset (transparency and consistency). Since it appears that Jason took it upon himself to consult Facebook for his own reasons (common friends, likes, and dislikes), and he is left “wondering what to do with the information,” it is unlikely that this is an official committee procedure, so Jason’s activities would not have been disclosed to the applicants. He thus violates the transparency requirement of the process. Furthermore it appears that Jason was able to glean the extra (not gathered from the first two stages) information only about applicants who used Facebook and had an open account. Jason’s method is therefore inconsistent, unlike the screening and interviewing stages, which all applicants undergo. Thus, if the committee were to consider Emily’s social networking activities, then the selection process would be neither transparent nor consistent, making it unjust because all applicants would not be receiving what they are owed from the onset. Were the committee to use this type of inconsistent information, www.virtualmentor.org Virtual Mentor, July 2011—Vol 13 449 which may be out of context (remember that at this point applicants cannot defend or explain this information), then it could be argued that determining which applicants actually deserve admission becomes obscured, potentially preventing deserving applicants from being admitted while undeserving applicants receive admission. In this way the process would meet neither justice criterion. Those who support use of social networking media in the selection process may say that the process is already unjust, as it is nearly impossible to know absolutely who does and does not deserve admission. Furthermore, if committees officially made social networking investigation part of their process, it would allow them access to more material with which to make a more informed decision. It can also be argued that, given the limited spots, not every applicant who deserves admission receives it, so the selection process is also unjust in this way. In response, I assert that, while there are inherent limitations on how much information the committee can gather in the first two stages due to finite interview time and class sizes, those limitations are consistent and institutionally enforced. For instance, all applicants are limited to the same number of characters in writing their personal statements, and all interviews last generally the same amount of time. Conversely, social networking sites are virtually limitless, and the amount and content of information is determined only by the user. If the committee were to disclose its utilization of Facebook, which it would be required to do if it made such sites an official part of the selection process, then an applicant would be free to alter and add information as he or she saw fit, in effect undermining the candid quality of Facebook that would have been attractive to the committee in the first place. In addition, some candidates may not have social networking accounts, making the process inconsistent, unless the committee required such accounts at the onset. Certain information fields would then need to be specified as mandatory, and the social networking account would become just another element in the formal application to be submitted during the screening stage. Although it is unfortunate that not all deserving applicants gain admission, I argue that it is not the committee’s job to grant admission to every deserving applicant; rather, they must ensure to the best of their ability that available space is filled only with deserving applicants—that it is as just a selection process as possible. A more pressing argument may be that future patients’ care is at stake if Emily harbors biases that may influence her ability to fulfill a physician’s responsibility to all patients. As a result, this argument goes, Jason has an obligation to inform the committee, even at the risk of making the selection process unjust. Here it is important to look more closely at Emily’s comments, which, when the “tone of disgust” is removed, essentially state her opinion against noncitizens who have illegally immigrated and are placing an apparent economic strain on American society. She is not necessarily morally opposed to immigrants or immigration in general. While immigrants (documented and undocumented) do not cost a disproportionate amount of money to treat, their treatment is more likely to be classified as uncompensated care [5], which, one could argue, can cause an economic Virtual Mentor, July 2011—Vol 13 www.virtualmentor.org 450 strain. It’s possible that Emily may decide in the future not to provide uncompensated care, meaning that patients who do not have health insurance will not receive her care. This may even include American citizens without insurance, since many fit this profile, although the percentage of uninsured is lower among citizens than non-citizens. In reality this is not unlike what is currently happening in health care; some physicians have decided not to provide services to the uninsured or even to patients who do have a particular level of insurance [6]. Another illustration of the fact that physicians can deny care is the legal protection they have in refusing to participate in abortions if they are religiously or morally opposed to doing so [7]. In fact no physician, simply because he or she is a physician, is required by any oath or law to treat all persons; physicians are traditionally held to the principle of nonmaleficence, but not necessarily that of beneficence. After all, Hippocratic writings say “help or at least do no harm” [8], indicating that above all physicians should not harm patients. Whether physicians are morally obligated to help all others is still debated among philosophers and ethicists. Any policies requiring physicians to treat all patients would most likely be contractually enforced by the individual practice or institution by which the physician is employed, and such requirements are not universal. While arguments can be made that patients should receive care regardless of their circumstances, whether or not such universal mandates should be placed upon physicians as a result is beyond the scope of this discussion. So although the physicians whose ranks Emily desires to join do treat a significant number of documented and undocumented immigrants, they are not universally required to do so. Therefore to deny Emily admission based upon her apparent bias is to impose upon her a requirement as a potential future physician that physicians are not currently subject to. Such imposition would be unfair unless all physicians had the same requirement, and, because it is not the admission committee’s place to impose requirements on current doctors, it should not consider her comments as detracting from her future ability to be a physician. Because the potential outcome of Emily’s bias would not prevent her from fulfilling the responsibilities of a current physician, Jason has no obligation to inform the committee, especially when doing so would cause the process to become unjust. Nevertheless, Emily’s comments do sound rather crass, most likely because she expressed her opinions in an unprofessional way. Indeed, unprofessional content posted on social networking sites is not uncommon, with 60 percent of medical schools reporting similar activities among their students [9]. However, professionalism has been identified, together with ethics and communication skills, as a competency that graduates of medical education must meet and that academic medical institutions must incorporate into their teaching [4]. While Emily did display unprofessional behavior in her comments, denying her admission would be undermining the recognized ability of medical students and graduates to grow into professional, respectful physicians as well as the medical institution’s ability to help its students become sensitive to and aware of cultural differences. Moreover, through www.virtualmentor.org Virtual Mentor, July 2011—Vol 13 451 lessons and personal experiences throughout medical training, it is perfectly reasonable to believe that Emily can learn to conduct herself appropriately in the future and even overturn her present bias. Emily’s responsibility is merely to be cautious of what she posts online; her medical training should subsequently prepare her to meet the professionalism standards of a physician. In summary, it would be unjust for the admission committee to consider social networking activities during the selection process because such practices would violate the principles of transparency (the application process does not state that networking activities are considered by the committee) and consistency (not all applicants post on social networks), while potentially denying deserving applicants due admission. Furthermore, use of such information may lead committees to impose upon applicants standards that are not imposed upon practicing physicians or professional values that the medical curriculum has a responsibility to cultivate in future physicians. References 1. Association of American Medical Colleges. Roadmap to Diversity: Integrating Holistic Review Practices into Medical School Admission Processes. Washington, DC: Association of American Medical Colleges; 2010. 2. Ridley A. Allocation and health care policy. In: Beginning Bioethics. New York: Bedford/St. Martin’s; 1997: 244-245. 3. Schwartz J. As jurors turn to Web, mistrials are popping up. New York Times. March 17, 2009. http://www.nytimes.com/2009/03/18/us/18juries.html?pagewanted=1&_r=1. Accessed July 28, 2010. 4. Liaison Committee on Medical Education (LCM). Functions and structure of a medical school: standards for accreditation of medical education programs leading to the MD degree. http://www.lcme.org/functions2010jun.pdf. Accessed July 28, 2010. 5. Stimpson JP, Wilson FA, Eschbach K. Trends in health care spending for immigrants in the United States. Health Aff (Millwood). 2010;29(3):544-550. 6. Sack K. As Medicaid payments shrink, patients are abandoned. New York Times. March 15, 2010. http://www.nytimes.com/2010/03/16/health/policy/16medicaid.html. Accessed July 29, 2010. 7. Sterilization or abortion. 42 USC sec 300a—7. http://www.law.cornell.edu/uscode/42/usc_sec_42_00000300---a007-.html. Accessed July 25, 2010. 8. Munson R. Major moral principles. In: Intervention and Reflection: Basic Issues in Medical Ethics. 7th ed. Belmont, MA: Thomson-Wadsworth; 2003. 9. Dolan PL. Social media behavior could threaten your reputation. American medical Association. http://www.ama- assn.org/amednews/2009/10/12/bil21012.htm. Accessed July 29, 2010. Virtual Mentor, July 2011—Vol 13 www.virtualmentor.org 452 Russell J. Coletti is a third-year student at the University of North Carolina School of Medicine in Chapel Hill. Related in VM Social Roles and Semi-Public Spaces on the Internet—The Case of Jason and Emily, July 2011 Jason’s Journal—Thoughts of an Ethically Conflicted Medical Student, July 2011 AMA Code of Medical Ethics’ Opinions on Confidentiality of Patient Information, July 2011 Anonymous Physician Blogging, July 2011 The viewpoints expressed on this site are those of the authors and do not necessarily reflect the views and policies of the AMA. Copyright 2011 American Medical Association. All rights reserved. www.virtualmentor.org Virtual Mentor, July 2011—Vol 13 453 http://virtualmentor.ama-assn.org/2011/07/conl2-1107.html http://virtualmentor.ama-assn.org/2011/07/conl3-1107.html http://virtualmentor.ama-assn.org/2011/07/coet1-1107.html http://virtualmentor.ama-assn.org/2011/07/ccas3-1107.html work_7ttu7inglzcpbb3cg5pogteide ---- wp-p1m-38.ebi.ac.uk Params is empty 404 sys_1000 exception wp-p1m-38.ebi.ac.uk no 221728940 Params is empty 221728940 exception Params is empty 2021/04/06-03:20:25 if (typeof jQuery === "undefined") document.write('[script type="text/javascript" src="/corehtml/pmc/jig/1.14.8/js/jig.min.js"][/script]'.replace(/\[/g,String.fromCharCode(60)).replace(/\]/g,String.fromCharCode(62))); // // // window.name="mainwindow"; .pmc-wm {background:transparent repeat-y top left;background-image:url(/corehtml/pmc/pmcgifs/wm-nobrand.png);background-size: auto, contain} .print-view{display:block} Page not available Reason: The web page address (URL) that you used may be incorrect. Message ID: 221728940 (wp-p1m-38.ebi.ac.uk) Time: 2021/04/06 03:20:25 If you need further help, please send an email to PMC. Include the information from the box above in your message. Otherwise, click on one of the following links to continue using PMC: Search the complete PMC archive. Browse the contents of a specific journal in PMC. Find a specific article by its citation (journal, date, volume, first page, author or article title). http://europepmc.org/abstract/MED/ work_7tukn3e4dvasllrx72go7jfuka ---- wp-p1m-39.ebi.ac.uk Params is empty 404 sys_1000 exception wp-p1m-39.ebi.ac.uk no 221744513 Params is empty 221744513 exception Params is empty 2021/04/06-03:20:44 if (typeof jQuery === "undefined") document.write('[script type="text/javascript" src="/corehtml/pmc/jig/1.14.8/js/jig.min.js"][/script]'.replace(/\[/g,String.fromCharCode(60)).replace(/\]/g,String.fromCharCode(62))); // // // window.name="mainwindow"; .pmc-wm {background:transparent repeat-y top left;background-image:url(/corehtml/pmc/pmcgifs/wm-nobrand.png);background-size: auto, contain} .print-view{display:block} Page not available Reason: The web page address (URL) that you used may be incorrect. Message ID: 221744513 (wp-p1m-39.ebi.ac.uk) Time: 2021/04/06 03:20:44 If you need further help, please send an email to PMC. Include the information from the box above in your message. Otherwise, click on one of the following links to continue using PMC: Search the complete PMC archive. Browse the contents of a specific journal in PMC. Find a specific article by its citation (journal, date, volume, first page, author or article title). http://europepmc.org/abstract/MED/ work_7wqsnggpgbb4fgd256t2zzumiy ---- 3_2001-UHE_UAB-16-05-2001.PDF 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 1 Chapter of the book: Ageyman, J. et al., Just Sustainabilities: Development in an Unequal World, Earthscan (forthcoming) Environmental Conflicts, Environmental Justice, and Valuation J. Martinez-Alier Universitat Autonoma de Barcelona [A]ABSTRACT In this article some historical and contemporary environmental conflicts are described. The international environmental liability of mining corporations is discussed. Comparisons are made with conflicts in the United States and in South Africa which fall under the rubric of the Environmental Justice movement. Such conflicts are fought out in many languages, and the economic valuation of damages is only one of such languages. Who has the power to impose particular languages of valuation? Who rules over the ways and means of simplifying complexity, deciding that some points of view are out of order? Who has power to determine which is the bottom-line in an environmental discussion? Key words: Ecological Distribution Conflicts/ Environmentalism of the Poor/ Environmental Justice/ Environmental Liability/ Copper mining/ Gold mining/ Ecological economics/ Valuation [A]INTRODUCTION There is a new tide in global environmentalism that arises from social conflicts on environmental entitlements, on the burdens of pollution, on the sharing of uncertain environmental risks, on the loss of access to natural resources and environmental services. Many such ecological distribution conflicts, whether they take place inside or outside markets, whether they are local or global, come about because economic growth means an increased use of the environment. In such ecological distribution conflicts, the poor are often at the side of resource conservation and a clean environment even when they themselves do not claim to be environmentalists. The claims to environmental resources and services of others who are differentially empowered and endowed, can be contested by arguing inside a single standard of value or across plural values. In this article, valuation of damages is discussed and also international environmental liability. The relations between ecological distribution conflicts and economic valuation are as follows. First, the pattern of 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 2 prices in the economy will depend on the concrete outcomes to ecological distribution conflicts. Second, ecological distribution conflicts (which often arise outside the market) are not fought only through demands for monetary compensation established in actual or fictitious market places. They may be fought out in other arenas. When the study of an ecological distribution conflict reveals a clash of incommensurable values, then this helps to develop an Ecological Economics which moves beyond the obsession of “taking nature into account” in money terms, and which is able therefore to cope with value pluralism. [A]ENVIRONMENTALISM AVANT-LA-LETTRE: COPPER MINING IN JAPAN I have chosen copper mining as a starting point, for two reasons. First, it provides historical examples. By looking at historical cases of environmental conflict which were not yet represented in the language of environmentalism, we can then interpret as environmental conflicts, instances of social conflict today where the actors are still reluctant to call themselves environmentalists (Guha, 1989). Second, by comparing historical with contemporary conflicts on copper mining, I make the point that copper has not become obsolete (despite aluminum and optic fiber). On the contrary, the frontier for the extraction of copper reaches new territories, and this is a good point to make against the believers in the “dematerialization” of the New Economy. Environmentalists in Japan remember Ashio as the site of Japan’s first major industrial pollution disaster. This was a large copper mine not far from Tokyo owned by the Fukurawa corporation, which witnessed a major workers’ riot against working conditions in 1907. Japanese social historians have debated whether the riot was “spontaneous” or organized by ancient brotherhoods. There were also already some “direct action” socialists in Japan at the time. While, as we shall see, in Rio Tinto in Andalusia in 1888 there was a common front between miners and peasants against pollution, this does not seem to have been so at Ashio, where tens of thousands of peasants along the Watarase river fought during decades against pollution from heavy metals which damaged not only crops but also human health. They also fought against the building of a large sediment basin to store the polluted waters, which implied the destruction of the village of Yanaka in 1907 including its cemetery and sacred shrines. “The mine’s refinery belched clouds containing sulfuric acid that withered the surrounding forests, and the waste water ... ran off into the Watarase River, reducing rice yields of the farmers who irrigated fields with this water... Thousands of farming families... protested many times. They petitioned the national authorities and clashed with the police. Eventually their leader, Tanaka Shozo, created a great stir by directly petitioning the emperor for relief...As environmental destruction reemerged in the 1960s as a major social issue, and popular concern with the impact of pollution intensified, so Ashio’s legacy as “the birthplace of pollution in Japan” has endured... At that time copper played a major role in the Japanese economy, ranking second to silk among Japan’s exports” (Nimura, 1997: 20-21, also Strong, 1977). Ashio was not 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 3 unique in the world, and Fukurawa’s own publicity remarked that Butte in Montana was a fearful place to live: “The smelting process has utterly destroyed the beauty of the landscape, evil gaseous smoke has killed all plant-life for miles round about; the streams are putrid with effluent, and the town itself seems buried under monstrous heaps of slag” (Strong, 1977: 67). Such were then the realities of copper mining in America. Ashio in comparison was not so bad except that, unlike Montana, there were thousands of unhappy peasants downstream.1 Fukurawa had bought the Ashio mines in 1877. In 1888 he made a deal for the supply to a French syndicate of 19,000 tons of copper over two and a half years, the target was met in full, three thousand miners were working then at Ashio, their number was to increase later to fifteen thousand. The contract with Fukurawa was signed on behalf of the French syndicate by the manager of Jardine Matheson, a firm founded by Sir James Matheson of the Lews, who was an uncle of Hugh Matheson, the founder of the Rio Tinto company (Strong, 1977: 67). Fukurawa procastinated for decades on anti- pollution measures, profiting from the novelty and uncertainty of the chemical pollution in question, and from the closeness between government and business in Japan. In cost-benefit language, it was argued: “Suppose for the sake of the argument that copper effluent were responsible for the damage to farmlands on either side of the Watarase - the public benefits that accrue to the country from the Ashio mine far outweigh any losses suffered in the affected areas. The damage can in any case be adequately taken care of by compensation” (article in the Tokio Nichi Nichi Shinbun of 10 Febr. 1892, in Strong, 1977: 74). In today’s parlance, a Pareto improvement means, in the strict sense, that a change such as a new mining project improves somebody’s situation, and does not worsen anybody’s situation. In this sense, Ashio did not fulfil the criterion. However, a Pareto improvement in a wider sense allows for compensation under the so-called Kaldor-Hicks rule, so that those better off can (potentially) compensate those worse off, and still a net gain be achieved. This was Fukurawa’s claim. Tanaka Shozo (1841-1913), the son of a peasant headman of a village in the polluted area, the leader of the anti-pollution struggles, could not yet have known about cost-benefit analysis and welfare economics. He became in the 1890s a member of the Diet in Tokyo famous for this fervent speeches, he was a man with deep religious feelings, the retrospective father figure of Japanese environmentalism - born therefore more in a tradition of pro-peasant environmental justice (and also of care for the urban ecology and concern for forest protection and the water cycle, Tamanoi et al. 1994) than wilderness preservation, although within a national context of industrialism and militarism which put environmentalism on the defensive. Today Japan is of course a big importer of copper through active transnational companies like Mitsubishi. Pollution from copper mining and smelting play still a big role in the ecological economies of some exporting countries. If world copper extraction was in 1900 of the order of 400,000 tons per year, one hundred years later it is of the order of 10 million tons, an increase by a factor of 25 (compared 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 4 to a fourfold increase in the human population, from 1.5 to 6 billion people between 1900 and 2000). Over 60 percent of copper production comes from such new mined ores, the rest from recycling, hence the relentless expansion of the copper frontier. The cheaper the cost of fresh extraction, the less recycling there is. Ashio was certainly not the only case of Japanese early popular environmentalism. Thus, when “the Nikko company built its copper refinery on the tip of the Saganoseki peninsula (in Oita Prefecture) in 1917, local farmers objected strenuosly. They feared that the acrid smoke from the refinery would blight the mountains and ruin the mulberry trees, on which their silk industry depended. Ignoring them the town officials agreed to the refinery. The farmers felt betrayed. The angry farmers swarmed into town and cut through the village leader’s house pillars, a tactic (uchikowashi) drawn straight from the Tokugawa period... The police brutally suppressed this protest, beating and arresting 100 participants. Nikko built the mill, and it operates to this day” (Broadbent, 1998: 138). [A]ONE HUNDRED YEARS OF POLLUTION IN PERU The Environmentalism of the Poor, and the Environmental Justice movement, are global cross-cultural movements, in all countries including the United States. (Guha, 2000). Work by several authors in the Central Sierra of Peru 25 years ago explained the successful defense of the communities both against expanding haciendas (Mallon, 1983). Indian shepherds’ and peasants’ resisted the “modernization” of the haciendas. Modern hacienda owners wanted to throw them out, and also their non-pedigreed sheep. The communities also had to struggle on another related front, against mining companies, and they still do. The Cerro de Pasco Copper Corporation polluted pasture lands in the 1920s and 1930s. Mines were not new to the Peruvian highlands. Huancavelica had supplied mercury to Potosi already in the 16th century. Silver had been mined in colonial and postcolonial times. Towards 1900, there was a world boom in copper, lead and zinc mining because of the proliferation of electrical instruments, tools, machines, armaments, railroads. Domestic capitalist miners were making small fortunes. In 1901 the Peruvian government changed the mining code, allowing private property of mining deposits (instead of state property and a regime of administrative concessions) (Dore, 2000:13-15). The Cerro de Pasco Corporation, from New York, bought many of the deposits, and started a large scale underground mining operation. The Cerro de Pasco company built roads, railroads, dams, hydroelectric plants, mining camps, at 4000 m. above sea level. It first built several small smelters, and then in 1922 a big smelter and refinery at La Oroya, the effects of which became a cause celebre. “The new smelter polluted the region’s air, soil and rivers with arsenic, sulphuric acid and iron-zinc residues” (Dore, 2000:14). The pastures withered, people became ill. There was a legal case brought against the company by peasant communities, and by old and new hacienda owners (some of whom were already at the time trying to modernize sheep raising), up to 120 km away. The mining company was forced by the court to buy the lands it had polluted, 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 5 as a form of indemnity. When in later years the mining operations and La Oroya smelter became less pollutant (at least with respect to the air, because of the scrubbers, if not with respect to the rivers), the property of all this land became a valuable asset for the company, which then started a large sheep ranching business, getting into border conflicts with surrounding communities. The enormous ranch (of about 300,000 ha) was expropriated in 1970 by the Land Reform, but still exists as the SAIS Tupac Amaru, owned by surrounding communities, one of the few large-scale sheep ranches in Peru which has not been taken over and split up into individual peasant communities. In the early 1900s, the Cerro de Pasco Corporation initially had difficulties in recruiting skilled labor. It resorted the enganche, a form of debt peonage. As Elizabeth Dore points out (Dore, 2000: 15), the large scale pollution caused by La Oroya smelter contributed to solving the labor shortage, because agricultural yields decreased in the small plots where agriculture is practiced at such altitude, and animals died. Peasant labor became available. This was another blessing in disguise. Mining in Peru was long dominated by the Cerro de Pasco Copper Corporation, but in the 1950s and 1960s, and increasingly until today, the main extraction of copper moved southward, towards Cuajone and Toquepala. These are large open-pit mines near Ilo, an extension of the rich deposits of Chuquicamata and other mines in northern Chile. The Southern Peru Copper Corporation owned by Asarco and Newmont Gold has subjected the city of Ilo, in southern Peru, of 60,000 inhabitants in the late 1990s, to water and air pollution for thirty years. The smelter was built in 1969, 15 km north of Ilo, it spewed daily almost two thousand tons of sulfur dioxide, while tailings and slag were discharged without treatment on land, and also on the ocean where, it was claimed, “several kilometres of coastline are totally black” (Ivonne Yanez, in the ELAN website, 4 October 1996). The actors are this time speaking on both sides an explicitly environmental language (Diaz Palacios, 1988, Balvin 1995). The Southern Peru Copper Corporation is Peru’s major single exporter. The conflict is more urban than it was in the central Sierra, and two appeals to international courts have been made. The local authorities presented a successful complaint in 1992 to the (unofficial) International Water Tribunal in the Netherlands in 1992, obtaining its moral support. A class-action suit was initiated at the District Court for the Southern District of Texas, Corpus Christi Division, in September 1995 but is was dismissed after the Peruvian state typically asked for the case to be brought back to Peru. The plaintiffs, on behalf of people from Ilo, most of them children with respiratory illnesses, complained that the pollution from sulfur dioxide had not appreciably decreased in the last years, despite the construction of a sulfuric acid plant (which recuperates sulfur dioxide). The federal court judge decided on 22 January 1996 against admitting the case into the U.S. judicial system on grounds of forum non conveniens. [A]THE STORY OF RIO TINTO AND OTHER STORIES 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 6 It was in Huelva, in the southern Spanish region of Andalusia in the 1880s, years before the words environment and ecology became common social coinage, that the first big environmental conflict associated with the name of Rio Tinto took place (Amery, 1974, Ferrero, 1994). The old royal mines of Rio Tinto were bought in 1873 by British and German interests, under Hugh Matheson, first chairman of the Rio Tinto Company. A new railway to the harbor of Huelva was immediately built, which was kindly made also available to local passengers on week-days (not on local holidays or Queen Victoria’s birthday). A very large open-pit mining operation was launched. Eighty years later, in 1954, the mines were sold back to new Spanish owners, the original Rio Tinto company keeping one-third interest. This British company Rio Tinto (renamed Rio Tinto Zinc) went on to become a worldwide mining and polluting giant (Moody, 1992) - its name, its business origins, its archive in London, all point to Andalusia, where a massacre by the Army on the 4th February 1888 of local farmers and peasants, and syndicalist miners, was the culmination of years of protests against sulfur dioxide pollution. Historians still debate the number of deaths caused when the Pavia Regiment opened fire against a large demonstration in the plaza of the village of Rio Tinto: “The company could not find out, and in any case soon decided it was better to play down the seriousness of the whole affair and gave up its attempts to discover the number of casualties, though Rio Tinto tradition puts the total number of dead at between one and two hundred” (Amery, 1974:207, also Ferrero, 1993: 83 ff.) . Historians also debate whether the miners complained only against the fact that excessive pollution prevented them from working on some days (days of manta, i.e. blanket) and therefore from earning full wages on those days, or whether they complained against pollution per se because of damage to their own and their families’ health. The company was taking out a large quantity of copper pyrites, employing some ten thousand miners. The idea was to sell the copper for export, and also as a by-product the sulfur in the pyrites (used for manufacturing fertilizers). The amount of ore extracted was so large, that in order to obtain the copper quickly, a lot of the sulfur was not recuperated but was thrown into the air as sulfur dioxide when roasting the ore in teleras in a process of open-air calcination, previous to smelting the concentrate. “The sulphurous fumes from the calcining grounds were a major cause of discontent. They produced an environment that everyone resented, for the pall of smoke which frequently hung over the area destroyed much of the vegetation and produced constant gloom and dirt” (Amery, 1974:192). Large and small farmers, though the company was paying monetary compensation to them, managed to convince some of the councils from small surroundings villages to forbid open-air calcination in their own municipal territories. The company successfully intrigued (through members of the Spanish Parliament in its pay) to segregate Rio Tinto as a municipal territory of its own (being part of the territory of Zalamea, a larger town), on the reasonable argument that population in the mining area had increased very much. The company was keen to have local municipal officers favorable to her. On the 4th February 1888, the immediate causes for the strike had been the complaint against the non-payment of full wages in manta days, and the demand for the abolition of piece-work and for the end of the deduction of one 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 7 peseta weekly from the wage bill to cover expenses of the medical fund. Maximiliano Tornet, the miners’ syndicalist leader, an anarchist who had been deported from Cuba back to Spain some years earlier, had managed to make an alliance with the peasants and farmers (and some landowners and local politicians) who had constituted the Huelva Anti-Smoke League. When the Army arrived in the plaza full of striking miners and peasants and peasant families from the region damaged by sulfur dioxide, an argument was going on inside the Rio Tinto town-hall on whether open-air teleras should be prohibited by municipal decree not only in surrounding villages but also in Rio Tinto itself. In terms of today’s language of environmental management, the local stakeholders (syndicalists, local politicians, peasants and farmers) did not achieve successful conflict resolution, let alone problem resolution. Had the municipality publicly announced a decree against open-air calcination, the tension in the plaza would have diminished, the strike would have been called off. Other stakeholders, that is, the Rio Tinto company and the civil governor in the capital of the province, were in the meantime mobilizing other resources, namely, arranging for troops to be brought into action. It is not known for sure who first shouted “fire”, perhaps a civilian from a window (Amery, 1974:205), but the soldiers understood the shout as an order to start shooting into the crowd.2 The popular interpretation of this episode in terms of environmentalism became unexpectedly relevant one hundred years later, as the village of Nerva, exactly in this region, struggled in the 1990s against the regional authorities over the siting of a large hazardous waste dump (precisely in a disused mine), local environmentalists and village officials explicitly appealing to the living memory of that “year of shots” of 1888 (Garcia Rey, 1997), fifty years before the Civil War of 1936-39, when the miners of Rio Tinto were massacred again, this time for non-ecological reasons. Meanwhile, sceptics on the thesis of popular environmentalism point out that, in 1888, the workers were more worried about wages that about pollution, and that the peasants and farmers were manipulated by local politicians who wanted to make money from the Rio Tinto company or who had their own disagreements with other politicians at national level on the treatment given to the British company - so conspicuously British that it sported an Anglican church and a cricket team.3 “Retrospective” environmentalism related to mining and air pollution is becoming a staple of social history in many countries. Not only air pollution, also water pollution (as in the Watarase river in Japan, and in Ilo, Peru) is important. It is present in other types of mining, for instance pollution by mercury, the azogue which the Spaniards employed in Potosi and also in Mexico to amalgamate with silver, and which today is used in Amazonian rivers to amalgamate with gold. Mercury was the origin of famous diseases in Japan from the 1950s onwards (though the consumption of fish), the best- known non-radioactive pollution episodes in the post-1945 history of Japan. Extraction of copper has been increasing at about 1.5 per cent per year still in the 1990s. If prices go down it is because of oversupply and not because of lack of 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 8 demand. I had planned already to include the following contemporary conflict, which now looks to me even more significant. In the late 1990s, in the region of Intag (Cotocachi, province of Imbabura) in northern Ecuador, Mitsubishi was defeated by a local non-governmental organization, Decoin, with help from Ecuadorian and international groups, in its plans to start mining for copper. I know this case first-hand, because of my relation with Accion Ecologica (Quito) which helped Decoin. The idea was to relocate one hundred families to make way for open-cast mining, bringing in thousand of miners in order to extract a large reserve of copper. This is a beautiful and fragile area of cloud forest and agriculture, with a mestizo population. Rio Tinto had already shown interest, but its previous incursions in Ecuador (at Salinas in Bolivar, at Molleturo in Azuay) ended in retreats. A Mitsubishi subsidiary, Bishi Metals, started in the early 1990s some preliminary work in Intag. After many meetings with the authorities, on May 12, 1997, a large gathering of members of affected communities resorted to direct action. Most of the company’s goods were inventoried and removed from the area (and later given back to the company), and the remaining equipment was burnt with no damage to persons. The government of Ecuador reacted by bringing a court case for terrorism (a rare event in Ecuador) against two community leaders and the leader of Decoin but the case was dismissed by the courts one year later. Attempts to bring in Codelco to mine (the Chilean national copper company) were also defeated, when Accion Ecologica from Quito sent one activist, Ivonne Ramos, to downtown Santiago to demonstrate with support from Chilean environmentalists on the occasion of a state visit of the president of Ecuador, and she was arrested. The publicity convinced Codelco to withdraw. Accion Ecologica also organized a visit by women belonging to the Intag communities, to copper mining areas in Peru, like Cerro de Pasco, La Oroya and Ilo. The women did their own interviews in those areas, and came back to Intag with their own impressions, carrying sad miners’ music and lyrics which became an immediate hit in Intag. These triumphant local women still deny to this day that they are environmentalists, or, God forbid, ecofeminists.4 Today there are several initiatives for alternative forms of development in Intag, one of them being the export of “organic” coffee to Japan arranged through environmental networks first contacted in the fight against Mitsubishi. But the copper ore is still there, underground, and the world demand for copper (despite calls for the “dematerialization” of the economy) keeps increasing. [A]BOUGAINVILLE AND WEST PAPUA Copper mining is more successful elsewhere, though not without conflicts. In the island of Bougainville, the Rio Tinto Zinc company got into trouble because of local opposition despite the agreement the company had made with the government of Papua New Guinea, which has sovereignty over Bougainville, in order to exploit the site of what was described as the most profitable copper and gold mine in the world. Back in 1974, it was reported that “the natives of Bougainville have stopped throwing geologists into the sea even since the company [Rio Tinto Zinc] declared itself willing to compensate them for the land it had taken with cash and other material services”. 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 9 However, it was also reported that monetary compensation was not enough: “The village communities affected gave the highest importance to land as the source of their material standard of life. Land was also the basis of their feelings of security, and the focus of most of their religious attention. Despite continuing compensation payments and rental fees, local resentment over the taking of the land remains high, and there is strong opposition to any expansion of mining in Bougainville, whether by the existing company, the government, or anyone else” (Mezger,1980:195). Finally, the tiny island of 160,000 inhabitant erupted into a secessionist war at the end of the 1980s. We notice here the use of languages such as sacredness, and national independence. We notice also that the language of monetary compensation was brought into play. Not far from Bougainville, the copper extraction frontier reached West Papua under Indonesia’s sovereignty, thirty years ago at a copper and gold mine called Grasberg owned by Freeport McMoRan from New Orleans, a company run by a colorful CEO, Jim Bob Moffet.5 Rio Tinto has a participation in this mine. The plans are in 2000 to mine daily 300,000 tons of ore, of which 98 per cent would be dumped into the rivers as tailings. The “ecological rucksack” of this operation includes of course not only the discarded tailings but also the overburden, that is all the materials removed before reaching the ore. The total copper content to be finally recovered would be nearly 30 million tons of copper, three years of world production, which would come into the market at a rate which would make of Grasberg the supplier of nearly ten per cent of world copper every year. This open cast mine is at high altitude, next to a glacier. The deposit originally formed the core of a 4,100 m. mountain, and the bottom of the open pit now lies at the 3,100 m. level. The current expansion would mean an annual extraction of ore that would allow an annual output of 900,000 tons of copper, and of 2.75 million ounces of gold.6 Water pollution in the Ajkwa river has been up to now the major environmental complaint, and acid drainage will be an increasing problem. The ecology of the island is particularly sensitive, and the scale of operations is enormous. In 1977, at the initial stages of operation, some Amungme rebelled, and destroyed the slurry pipeline carrying copper concentrate to the coast. Reprisals by the Indonesian army were terrible. Many complaints against Freeport McMoRan led to an initially unsuccessful class-action suit in New Orleans in April 1996 by Tom Beanal and other members of the Amungme tribe. Tom Beanal declared (at a speech at Loyola University, New Orleans, 23 May 1996): “These companies have taken over and occupied our land...Even the sacred mountains we think of as our mother have been arbitrarily torn up, and they have not felt the least bit guilty... Our environment has been ruined, and out forests and rivers polluted by waste... We have not been silent. We protest and are angry. But we have been arrested, beaten and put into containers: we have been tortured and even killed”. Tom Beanal was reported to have gotten some money from the company for his own NGO, an attempt at a classic procedure for conflict resolution, but the legal case made some progress in the Louisiana courts in March 1998 on the issue of whether U.S. courts could have jurisdiction. The best-known representative of the Amungme is now Yosepha Alomang, subjected to detention in horrible conditions in 1994, and who was 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 10 prevented from leaving the country in 1998 when she wanted to attend a Rio Tinto’s shareholders’ meeting in London.7 Some Freeport’s shareholders have been publicly concerned about the liabilities incurred by the company in Indonesia. Henry Kissinger is a director of Freeport. The company was deeply involved with the Suharto regime, having given shares in the company to relatives and associates of the ex- President. Freeport is also the biggest source of tax revenue for Indonesia. Which line will the new Indonesian government, and also the separatist movement in West Papua (Organisasi Papua Merdeka, OPM), take towards plans by Freeport (and Rio Tinto) to expand the extraction of copper and gold ore? The OPM has staged ceremonies raising the Papuan flag in the last thirty years, answered violently by the Indonesia Army and by Freeport’s security forces (one famous instance took place on Christmas Day of 1994 at Tembagapura, a locality near the Grasberg mine). Will claims for an ecological debt to be paid by Freeport McMoRan be made not through a private class-action suit brought by indigenous tribes but as a result of an Indonesian governmental action, an international replica of a Superfund case in the United States? Attempts to obtain indemnities for international externalities caused by TNCs outside their legal country of residence are interesting ingredients in the calculation of the many environmental liabilities which the North owes to the South, the sum of which would amount to a large ecological debt. The Indonesian state had an authoritarian regime (or less politely, it was a capitalist dictatorship) from the mid-1960s until the end of the 1990s. The circumstances in West Papua (or Irian Jaya, this being at the time the official Indonesian name) with both a very rich mine and a separatist movement, provided reasons for a heavy military presence. It would be a cruel joke to say that a suitable environmental policy (implementing the “polluter pays principle”) would have allowed externalities to be internalized into the price of exported copper and gold. Environmental economists forget to include the distribution of political power in their analysis. Some of them even believe in their touching innocence that environmental damages arise because of “missing markets”. In fact, externalities should be seen in general not as “market failures” but as “cost-shifting successes” (Martinez-Alier and O’Connor, 1996, 1999). The language of indigenous territorial rights (whose official acceptance would be a novelty in Indonesia), and even the stronger language of a separate national Papuan identity (which is historically relevant, since West Papua was annexed by Indonesia after the departure of the Dutch), may be used nowadays after the end of the dictatorship in order to fight the human and environmental disaster caused by the world’s largest gold mine and the third-largest copper mine. Freeport McMoRan is building in 2000 with Mitsubishi a large smelter at Gresik in Java, for export of copper to Japan. Freeport McMoRan also happens to own in Huelva, Spain, the firm Atlantic Copper which is the successor of the copper smelting and refining operation of the Spanish Rio Tinto company formed after 1954, and 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 11 where copper concentrate from Grasberg is taken. It is all as a large family. In international purely political conflicts without real substance, such as a dispute between states over a strip of useless territory, by reaching a peace agreement and drawing a new frontier, both the conflict and the problem disappear. Sometimes, as in the last twenty years for the threat by CFC to the ozone layer, or for transboundary sulfur dioxide emissions in Europe, agreements are reached which lead to regimes that solve both the conflict and the problem. Instead, in many other environmental cases, solving the conflict is not equivalent to solving the problem. In order to advance towards problem-resolution, what is then needed is not conflict-resolution, but conflict-exacerbation. [A]A FEW GOLD MINING CONFLICTS Gold is sometimes produced together with other metals, such as copper, but is often the primary objective in mining enterprise. Gold mining is similar in a sense to shrimp farming, or to the extraction of tropical wood like mahogany. Its demand is directly driven by consumption. About 80 per cent of all gold that is dug out of the ground ends up as jewelry. Now, however, is consumption the real driver of the economy? Are not changes of techniques the real drivers of capitalism, and are they not introduced in production, rather than consumption, because of the pressures of competition and profits? Moreover, could not enough consumption to maintain production levels be secured already by the incomes gained in relatively dematerialized activities - a Seattle economy without Boeing? Interesting but premature questions, because the economy is not dematerializing and because consumption has a life of its own, it is not determined by the necessity to sell production. The economy is driven by the profit-rate. It also driven by conspicuous consumption or the wish to obtain positional goods. Hence the use of increased incomes in order to buy more and more gold, a habit of the human species in which the East and the West truly meet. The price of gold makes it still profitable to open new mines. Gold lasts a very long time but the existing stock of gold in the world, counting also the central banks’ reserves, does not seem to satisfy humankind’s desires, and there is pressure to open new mines not to substitute for gold which is lost but to accumulate new stocks. Why do not the central banks sell the gold they have? Some religions forbid consumption of shrimps or pork or beef or other types of food. Is there any religion that forbids the mining and accumulation of gold? Gold mining is particularly destructive, both when it is small-scale (as the garimpeiros in Brazil) and when it is large-scale by corporations such as Placer Dome, Newmont, or Freeport or Rio Tinto or Anglo- American. Gold leaves behind enormous “ecological rucksacks”, and also pollution from mercury or cyanide. The participants at a Peoples’ Gold Summit in San Juan Ridge, California, which was 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 12 held on June 2-8, 1999, asked for a moratorium on the exploration for gold. The manifesto coming out of this meeting begins: “Life, land, clean water and clean air are more precious than gold. All people depend on nature for life. The right to life is a guaranteed human right. It is, therefore, our responsibility to protect all of nature for present and future generations. Large-scale gold mining violently uproots and destroys the spiritual, cultural, political, social and economic lives of peoples as well as entire ecosystems. Historic and current destruction created by gold mining is greater than any value generated.8 Commercial gold mining projects are mainly on indigenous lands. By violating their land rights mining companies are denying the right to life of those indigenous peoples, whose relationship to land is central to their spiritual identity and survival. We need to support the self-determination of indigenous peoples and the recovery, demarcation and legal recognition of campesinos, tribal and indigenous peoples’ lands... Large-scale and small-scale, toxic chemical-dependent gold mining damages landscapes, habitats, biodiversity, human health and water resources. Water especially is contaminated by cyanide, acid mine drainage, heavy metals and mercury from gold mining. Additionally, the hydrological cycle is changed and water sources are grossly depleted by pumping water from aquifers”. There is no space here to describe in detail the conflict in Peru, at the time of writing, between the Yanacocha mine in Cajamarca (where Atahualpa met Pizarro) and local communities that belong to the Federacion de Rondas Campesinas. The gold mine is owned by Newmont, and also by a local company, with a 5% share belonging to the International Finance Corporation of the World Bank. In Venezuela, under the government that preceded President Hugo Chavez, Decree 1850 of 1997 tried to open up the forest reserve area of Imataca of three million ha to gold mining. A movement arose which comprised the sparse local indigenous Pemon population, some environmental groups such as Amigransa (the friends of the Gran Sabana), some anthropologists and sociologists, and some members of Parliament. They all used different languages (from Indian demonstrations in the streets of Caracas to legal appeals to the Supreme Court) in the service of the same cause. They managed for the time being to stop mining in Imataca. The environmental commission of the Chamber of Deputies of Venezuela appealed to the Supreme Court against Decree 1850, quoting a figure between US$ 7 thousand and 23 thousand per hectare for the restoration of the vegetable cover affected by oil exploitation, a useful if moderate figure in order to calculate the large environmental liabilities that gold mining, with its toxic effects and large ecological rucksacks, implies.9 [A]ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE “Environmental Justice” is not an expression taken, as one would expect, from philosophy or ethics but from environmental sociology and from the study of race relations. In the United States it has come to mean since the late 1980s and early 1990s an organized movement against “environmental racism, i.e. the disproportionate allocation of toxic waste to Latino or African-American communities. It is also relevant for Indian reservations in the United States, 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 13 particularly in the context of uranium mining and nuclear waste. Indeed, “environmental justice” could subsume historic conflicts on sulfur dioxide, the Chipko and Chico Mendes cases, the current conflicts on the use of carbon sinks, the conflicts on oustees from dams, the fight for the preservation of rainforests or mangroves for livelihood, and many other cases around the world which sometimes have to do with “racism” and sometimes not. The Environmental Justice movement in the United States (Bullard, 1990,1993, Pulido, 1991, 1996, Bryant and Mohai, 1992, Bryant, 1995, Sachs, 1995, Gottlieb, 1993, Szasz, 1994, Schwab, 1994, Westra and Wenz, 1995, Dorsey, 1997, Faber, 1998, DiChiro, 1998, Camacho, 1998, Taylor, 2000) is quite different from the two previous environmentalisms in this country, namely, the efficient and sustainable use of natural resources (in the tradition of Gifford Pinchot), and the cult of wilderness (in the tradition of John Muir). As a self-conscious movement, Environmental Justice fights against the alleged disproportionate dumping of toxic waste or exposure to different sorts of environmental risk in areas of predominantly African-American, or Hispanic or Native-American populations. The language employed is not that of uncompensated externalities but rather the language of race discrimination, which is politically powerful in the United States because of the long Civil Rights struggle. In fact, the organized Environmental Justice movement is not an outgrowth of previous currents of environmentalism but rather an outgrowth of the Civil Rights movement. Thus, in the Third World, the main socio-environmental question was in the 1980s whether an indigenous, independent Environmentalism of the Poor existed, a question first theorized in India and, later, in Latin America and Africa, because of episodes of defense of common property resources against the State or the Market (Martinez-Alier and Guha, 1997, 1999). Meanwhile, in the United States the question was whether the buoyant mainstream environmental movement would deign to consider the existence of “environmental racism”, whether it could accept and work with “minorities” which were mainly concerned with urban pollution. There are many cases of local environmental activism in the United States by “citizen- workers groups” (Gould et al., 1996) outside the organized Environmental Justice movement, some with one-hundred years’ roots in the many struggles for health and safety in mines and factories, perhaps also in complaints against pesticides in Southern cotton fields, and certainly in the struggle against toxic waste at Love Canal in upstate New York led by Lois Gibbs (Gibbs, 1981, 1995) who also later led a nation-wide “toxics-struggles” movement showing that poor communities would not tolerate any longer being dumping grounds (Hofrichter, 1993). In the “official” Environmental Justice movement are included celebrated episodes of collective action against incinerators (because of the uncertain risk of dioxins), particularly in Los Angeles, led by women. Also in the 1980s, other environmental conflicts gave rise to groups such as People for Community Recovery in South Chicago (Altgeld Gardens), led by Hazel Johnson, and the West Harlem Environmental Action (WHEACT) in New York, led by Vernice Miller. In 1989, the South-West Network for Economic 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 14 and Environmental Justice (SNEEJ), led by Richard Moore, was founded, with its main seat in Albuquerque, New Mexico, out of grievances felt by Mexican and Native American populations. In October 1991 the First National People of Color Environmental Leadership Summit took place in Washington D.C., the Principles of Environmental Justice were proclaimed, and the movement for Environmental Justice became well known. President Clinton’s Executive Order 12,898 of 1994 on Environmental Justice was a triumph for this movement. It directed all federal agencies (though not corporations or private citizens) to act in such a way that disproportionate burdens of pollution do not fall on low income and minority populations in all territories and possessions of the United States. Thus, both poverty and race were taken into account, and nothing was said about impacts outside the United States. Happy the country where “low-income” people are regarded as a minority (alongside or overlapping with racial “minorities”)! The insistence on “environmental racism” is sometimes surprising to analysts from outside the United States. In fact, some foreign academics refuse to acknowledge the racial angle, and have boldly stated that: “If one were asked to date the beginning of the environmental justice movement in the United States, then 2 August 1978 might be the place to start. This was the day when the CBS and ABC news networks first carried news of the effect of toxic waste on the health of the people of a place called Love Canal” (Dobson, 1998:18). However, the Love Canal people, led by Lois Gibbs, were not people of color, they were white, as such categories are understood in the U.S., and therefore were subject only to metaphorical, not real “environmental racism”. Other non-U.S. academics agree with the interpretation that Environmental Justice is in the U.S. a movement against “environmental racism”. I also agree. Thus, the seminal moment (Low and Gleeson, 1998: 108) was in 1982 in Warren County, North Carolina. Of course, one could also argue that the world environmental justice movement started long ago at a hundred dates and places all over the world. For instance, in Andalusia in 1888, when miners and peasants at Rio Tinto were massacred by the army. Or when Tanaka Shozo threw himself in front of the Emperor’s carriage with a petition in his hand. Or, in the United States, not in North Carolina but in the struggles against mining corporations in Wisconsin conducted by alliances of Indian tribes and environmentalists in the 1970s and 1980s (Gedick, 1993), and in many other struggles of resistance by Native Americans, from Canada to Tierra del Fuego. Which will be the worldwide First of May or Eighth of March of Environmental Justice and the Environmentalism of the Poor? Chico Mendes’ assassination day, Ken Saro-Wiwa’s, or perhaps the day the Rainbow Warrior was sunk by the French secret services in New Zealand, and its Portuguese cook died? Or when Karunamoi Sardar died defending her village in Horinkhola, Khulna, Bangladesh, on 7 November 1990?10 The self-conscious Environmental Justice movement in the United States of the 1980s and 1990s shifted the whole discussion about environmentalism in the United States away from preservation and conservation of Nature towards social justice. It 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 15 destroyed also the NIMBY image of grassroots environmental protests by turning them into NIABY protests (not in anyone’s backyard). Also, it expanded the circle of people involved in environmental policy by practicing “post-normal science” in the “popular epidemiology” movement. In the United States, the legislation against racism (such as Title VI of the Federal Civil Rights Act of 1964) forbids discrimination based on race. However, in order to establish the existence of racism, it is not sufficient to prove that environmental impact is different (for instance, that lead in children’s blood level is different according to racial background). It must also be shown that there an explicit intention to cause harm to a minority group. The uncertainties of environmental risk (for instance, dioxin), and the statistical difficulties in separating racial and economic factors in toxic waste location decisions, have given rise to a rich practice of “popular epidemiology” (Novotny, 1998). It might be difficult to prove that race more than poverty correlates with toxic waste, but if this is convincingly shown, then the chances of redress are high. Lay persons gather scientific data and other information, and they also process the results offered by official experts in order to challenge them in cases involving toxic pollution, a clear case of “extended peer review”. By emphasizing “racism”, the movement for Environmental Justice also emphasizes incommensurableness of values. This is its greatest achievement. If I pollute a poor neighborhood, by applying the polluter pays principle (PPP), I may compensate the damage. This is more easily written than done, because, how much is human health worth? In which scale of value? Nevertheless, the PPP implies that a worsening ecological distribution is in principle compensated by an improving economic distribution. The objective is of course to make pollution expensive enough so that its level will decrease by a change in technology or by a lower level of polluting production. Whatever the objective, the principle implies a single scale of value. Now, the same problem phrased in terms of “environmental racism” becomes a different problem. I can inflict damage to human dignity by using a racial insult or by racial discrimination. Paying a fine does not entitle me to repeat such conduct. There is no real compensation. Money and human dignity are not commensurate. Bullard, who is both an academic and an activist, realizes the potential of the Environmental Justice movement beyond “minority” populations, and asserted in 1994: “Grassroots groups, after decades of struggle, have grown to become the core of the multi-issue, multi-racial, and multi-regional environmental justice movement. Diverse community-based groups have begun to organize and link their struggles to issues of civil and human rights, land rights and sovereignty, cultural survival, racial and social justice, and sustainable development... Whether in urban ghettos and barrios, rural “poverty pockets”, Native American reservations, or communities in the Third World, grassroots groups are demanding an end to unjust and non-sustainable environmental and development policies...”.11 Notice then the clear awareness that environmental justice is functional to sustainability, and that it concerns poor people everywhere, including indeed Third World communities, that is, billions of people. 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 16 Low-income “people of color” are a minority in the U.S. but they are certainly a majority in the world at large. There are some ecological distribution conflicts in the world (the European conflicts on nuclear risks as expressed at famous fights in Gorleben or Creys-Malville, or again the European conflict against U.S. “hormone beef” and transgenic crops, or the current conflict on the Three Gorges dam in China, for instance), for the analysis and resolution of which, the metaphor of “environmental racism” is not useful. On the other hand, we could retrospectively apply “environmental racism” to one of the many forms of racism that the Spaniards showed in America, by imposing a terrible load of mercury poisoning to indigenous workers in silver mines (Dore, 1999). Environmental racism is often a useful language for conflicts which have been fought up to now under the banner of indigenous territorial rights. Activists and lawyers in the class action suit against Texaco from Ecuador, blamed Texaco in advertisements in U.S. newspapers in 1999 for “environmental racism”. Profiting from the publicity against Texaco because of a court case for internal racism against black employees in the United States (settled out of court in 1997 for US$ 176 million), sympathizers for the Ecuadorian plaintiffs placed an advertisement in the New York Times (23 Sept. 1999) which stated: “The lawsuit alleges that in Ecuador, Texaco dumped the poisonous water produced by oil drilling directly onto the ground, in nearby rivers, and in streams and ponds. The company knowingly destroyed the surrounding environment and endangered the lives of the indigenous people who had lived and fished there for years. These are people of color, people for whose health and well-being Texaco shows only a cavalier disregards... It’s time that Texaco learns that devaluing the lives and well-being of people because of the color of their skin is no longer acceptable for any American company”. Notice that this language, so effective in the United States, was not used when the case started in 1993, and it would be problematic though not impossible to apply it to Texaco’s successor, Petroecuador, which has used similar technology damaging not only indigenous people but also average mestizo Ecuadorian settlers. Perhaps “internal colonialism” (Adeola, 2000) could be used against Petroecuador, as against the Nigerian authorities, while “racism” could be reserved for Texaco (or Shell, in Nigeria). [A]INTERNATIONAL ENVIRONMENTAL LIABILITIES Environmental conflicts in South Africa are often phrased in the language of environmental justice (Bond, 2000). Thus, a conflict in the late 1990s which continues at the time of writing places environmentalists and local populations against a project near Port Elizabeth for the development of an industrial zone, a new harbor, and a smelter of zinc for export, owned by Billinton, a British firm which would guzzle up electricity and water at cheap rates while poor people cannot get the small amounts of water and electricity they desperately need, or in any case must pay increasing rates under current economic policies . The Billinton project has costs in terms of tourists’ revenues because of the threats to a proposed national elephant park extension nearby, 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 17 to beaches, estuaries, islands and whales (Bond, 2000:47). There are also costs in terms of the displacement of people from the village of Coega. This point was emphasized in a letter sent by the Southern Africa Environment Project to Peter Mendelson, the British Secretary of State for Trade and Industry: “We are writing on behalf of those who have historically lacked the capacity to assert their rights and protect their own interests but who now seek to be heard and to call to the attention of the international community the injustice that is now about to be inflicted upon them”. The life of the people of Coega was already full of memories of displacements under the racist regime of apartheid. Although Billinton could no longer profit from the lack of voice of the people under apartheid, now -it was alleged- it sought “to take advantage of the region’s desperate need for employment to enable construction of a highly polluting facility that would never be allowed adjacent to a major population centre in the U.K. or any other European country”.12 A small improvement in the economic situation of the people would be obtained at high social and environmental cost, because of displacement of people, and also because of increased levels of sulfur dioxide, heavy metals, dust, liquid effluents. An appeal was made to British Minister to take into account OECD’s guidelines for multinational enterprises which include a chapter on environmental protection since 1991, but which are no more than recommendations which the authorities cannot enforce directly. The Minister was asked in any case to exercise his influence upon Billinton informally. The environmental impacts which the apartheid regime left behind are now surfacing. There are large liabilities to be faced. Best known is the asbestos scandal, which includes international litigation initiated by victims of asbestosis against British companies, particularly Cape. Nearly 2000 persons asked for compensation because of personal damages as a result of Cape’s negligence in supervising, producing and distributing asbestos products. The lawyers argue that Cape was aware of the dangers of asbestos at least from 1931 onwards, when Britain asbestos regulations were introduced. Nevertheless production continued in South Africa with the same low safety standards until the late 1970s. Medical researchers have found that 80 per cent of Penge’s black miners (in Northern Province) who died between 1959 and 1964 had asbestosis. The average age of the victims was 43. Cape operated a mill for 34 years in Prieska, Northern Cape, where 13 per cent of workers’ deaths were attributed to mesothelioma, a very painful asbestos related cancer. Asbestos levels in this mill in 1948 were almost 30 times the maximum UK limit. There are other cases in South Africa of asbestos contamination, by companies such as Msauli and GEFCO, at locations such as Mafefe, Pomfret, Barberton, Badplass (Felix, in Cock and Koch, 1991). Contaminated abandoned mines and asbestos dumps must nowadays be rehabilitated by the post-apartheid South African governments. Simultaneously, court cases were started against Cape in the U.K., and the House of Lords (in its judicial capacity) ruled for a while (until July 1999, when the judgement was reversed) that such cases could be heard in London rather than in South Africa. It seemed that British companies 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 18 could be sued in British courts. Against GATT-WTO doctrine, the asbestos court case and similar ones, if successful, would show that international regulation is required not only about the safety and quality of the final products but also on the process of production and its side-effects. When regulation failed or was non-existent, and when effective protest was impossible because of political repression, there are then retrospective liabilities to be faced. The courts will perhaps institute little by little a sort of international Superfund obligations for the transnational companies. True, the South African apartheid state was blind to damage to black workers. The asbestos and mining companies most probably fulfilled internal South African laws as regards safety, wages, and taxes. Nevertheless, they should be held accountable for the “externalities” that they left behind. Given the chance, workers and their families would have complained, not so much because they were environmentalists but because their health was threatened. The law firm which represents the asbestosis victims (Leigh, Day) also brought actions in London for damages to workers at Thor Chemicals in KwaZulu-Natal on behalf of victims of poisoning by mercury, and on behalf of cancer victims from Rio Tinto’s Rossing uranium mine in Namibia.13 In April 1990 massive concentrations of mercury had been detected in the Umgeweni River near the Thor Chemicals’ Cato Ridge plant. This was reported in the national and international press. Thor Chemicals imported mercury waste into South Africa, partly supplied by Cyanamid, an American company. South African environmental groups, mainly Earthlife under Chris Albertyn’s leadership, allied themselves with the Chemical Workers Industrial Union, the local African residents under their chief, and also white farmers from the Tala Valley who had already endured a bad experience of pesticide spraying from the neighboring sugar industry. A true “rainbow” alliance, which also incorporated U.S. activists against the Cyanamid plant in question, complained against such “garbage imperialism” or “toxic colonialism” by asking: “Why did Thor, a British company, decide to build the world’s larget toxic mercury recycling plant on the borders of KwaZulu in a fairly remote part of South Africa? Why not build it closer to the sources of the waste mercury in the United States or in Europe?” (Crompton and Erwin, in Cock and Koch eds., 1991:82-84). Actually, “the practice of exporting hazardous wastes for disposal in developing countries has been described as environmental injustice or environmental racism on a global scale”. (Lipman, 1998). The Basel Convention of 1989 forbids the export of hazardous waste from rich countries except for recovery of raw materials or for recycling. It was complemented on 25 March 1994 by a full ban negotiated at a meeting in Geneva on all exports of hazardous waste from the 24 rich industrialized countries of the OECD. The agreement was reached over the opposition of the richest countries, which received from Greenpeace, in this context, the name of the Sinister Seven. Some defections inside the European Union (Denmark, and later Italy) helped an alliance among China, Eastern European countries, and in general all southern poor countries in order to close in theory the “recycling” loophole of the initial 1989 convention though which ninety per cent of the waste was flowing. Thus, pending 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 19 ratification and domestic implementation of this agreement, and assuming also that Article 11 of the Basel Convention (which allows for bilateral or multilateral hazardous waste exporting agreements provided they comply with “environmentally sound management”) is not abused, then a sad chapter of industrialization would be closed. Rich countries would not be able to exploit the weaker regulations of poorer countries to avoid their own responsibility for minimizing waste. Clearly, the issue is far from over. The pressure for the export of toxic waste still increases, although the Basel Convention has had a positive effect. This is the context in which in November 1998 it was announced that nearly 3,000 tons of Taiwanese toxic waste from the group Formosa Plastics had been dumped in a field in the port of Sihanoukville in Cambodia. Taiwan is not a party to the Basel Convention. The waste was scavenged by poor villagers, many of whom later complained of sickness; one died quickly. (Human Rights Watch, 1999). The logic of Lawrence Summers’ Principle still remains compelling.14 The perception of risk changes with time, sometimes because scientific research produces clear results, sometimes because, on the contrary, scientific uncertainties cannot be dispelled, and a feeling of danger creeps in. Then, the question is asked: Who is responsible for cleaning up the (newly perceived) mess, or for paying indemnities or making reparations? How to assign environmental liabilities, granting that restoration may be impossible when irreversible damages or deaths are involved? Thus, the “Superfund” legislation in the United States is supposed to achieve the cleaning up of hazardous waste sites (chemical dumps, mine tailings...), which are called “orphaned” when no existing corporation or private citizen or public body is responsible. In this exceptional case, the burden of proof lies rather with polluting companies than with the polluted citizens or with the regulatory agency. Companies have to prove against EPA’ allegations that no risk of damage exists from the waste they have abandoned. Nuclear waste is excluded however from the Superfund legislation, which arose in the late 1970s (at the end of President Carter’s administration). Its official name is Comprehensive Environmental Response Compensation and Liability Act (CERCLA). As in Europe after the Seveso alarm (dioxin release from a chemical firm near Milan), in the United States after the Love Canal scandal near Niagara Falls in upper state New York, there was a feeling that something should be done to remedy damage done, and to make future damage costly by imposing strict norms of private or public liability. Superfund may also be interpreted as a government response to the first stirrings of the environmental justice movement. Cleaning up operations under Superfund are financed by special charges on the oil and chemical industries, when the sites are “orphaned”. When the companies are identified and still active, they have to pay for the cleaning up. The EPA must not act in an “arbitrary and capricious” manner but it has no obligation to prove that there is actual damage, only that there is a risk of damage. Critics of Superfund point out that the costs are too high compared to benefits, including administrative costs, and that the communities near the waste sites cleaned up do not always benefit economically because the improved environmental situation is 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 20 countered by the adverse environmental image. Notice that there is no international Superfund to which appeal can be made, should common-law judicial actions against Texaco, FreeportMacMoRan, Dow Chemical, Cape or the Southern Peru Copper Corporation fail. After listing a number of cases in the United States in which indemnities have been paid by corporations, such as the Exxon Valdez, a Venezuelan journalist asked himself in January 2000: “Being Venezuela a country dominated by the oil and mining industries, the question is, which is the pasivo ambiental (i.e. environmental liability) of all this oil and mining activity in our country?”15 It is fascinating to watch the diffusion of the term pasivo ambiental in a mining and oil extraction context in Latin America as one writes this article. Hector Sejenovich, from Buenos Aires, was perhaps the first economist to use this term when he calculated the environmental liabilities from oil extraction in the province of Neuquen, Argentina. The Argentinian Minister for the Environment Oscar Massei was quoted on 6 February 200 ( journal Rio Negro, on line) as saying that regional incentives to oil companies in Neuquen may not include flexibilization of environmental standards. The government, he added ominously, had in its possession the study made for UNDP which evaluated the pasivos ambientales from oil exploitation in Neuquen at one billion dollars. In Peru, a new law project was submitted to Congress in 1999 (project n. 786) creating an National Environmental Fund - as sort of internal GEF as a congressman put it. The Fund would finance environmental research, it would improve and restore the environment, and would promote ecological agriculture. Its economic resources would come mainly from a percentage of the revenue from the privatization of state enterprises. After complaining about the environmental deterioration in the last decades because of mining and fisheries, after commenting on increasing desertification and deforestation in the country, congressman Alfonso Cerrate quoted the case of the privatization of CENTROMIN (the State firm which was the successor to the Cerro de Pasco Copper Corporation), which was not successful. The environmental problems of Centromin must have been a factor in the lack of buyers at the auction. The question was, “who will pay for the ecological debt? Who will assume the environmental liability (pasivo ambiental) accumulated throughout the years by CENTROMIN and other state firms?” In Chile, new legislation on liabilities after closing mines was being discussed in 1999 and 2000. The Sociedad Nacional de Mineria was aware that environmental standards should improve, that there was a danger of being internationally accused of ecological dumping, and it was in favor of applying international environmental standards adapted of course to national realities. En el tema del pasivo ambiental, it added, discussions were proceeding but the general feeling in the industry was that the State should assume such environmental liabilities.16 The Bolivian vice-minister of Mines, Adan Zamora, referring to the pollution in the river Pilcomayo (that flows down from Potosi towards Tarija and eventually Argentina), increased by the bursting of a 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 21 tailings dyke at Porco belonging to Comsur, had said in 1998: la nueva politica estatal minero-metalurgica tiene como responsabilidad remediar los pasivos ambientales originados en la actividad minera del pasado (Presencia, 16 June 1998). In fact, environmental liabilities in Potosi reach back to the 16th century. [A]CONCLUSIONS Driven by consumption, the throughput of energy and materials in the world economy has never been so large as today. Paradoxically, increases in eco-efficiency lead sometimes to increased demands of material and energy, because their costs diminish (the Jevons effect). Externalities will not decrease but on the contrary, increase because the growth of the world economy. We are certainly not in a “post-material” age. Externalities (i.e. cost-shifting) must be seen as part and parcel of the economy, which is necessarily open to the entry of resources and to the exit of residues. The appropriation of resources and the production of waste result in ecological distribution conflicts, which give rise to a worldwide Environmental Justice movement which in fact started many years ago. The Environmentalism of the Poor and the movement for Environmental Justice (local and global), grown from the complaints against the appropriation of communal environmental resources and against the disproportionate burdens of pollution, may help to move society and economy in the direction of ecological sustainability. Activists of the U.S. Environmental Justice movement have emphasized the links between the increasing globalization of the economy and environmental degradation of habitats for many of the world’s peoples: “In many places where Black, minority, poor or Indigenous peoples live, oil, timber and minerals are extracted in such a way as to devastate eco-systems and destroy their culture and livelihood. Waste from both high- and low-tech industries, much of it toxic, has polluted groundwater, soil and the atmosphere. Environmental degradation such as this, and its concomitant impact on human wealth and welfare, is increasingly seen as violation of human rights”. As mining, logging, oil drilling and waste-disposal projects push into further corners of the planet, people all over the world are seeing their basic rights compromised, losing their livelihoods, cultures and even their lives. “Environmental devastation globally and what we call “environmental racism” in the United States, are violations of human rights and they occur for similar reasons”.17 The management and resolution of such ecological distribution conflicts requires cooperation between business, international organizations, NGO networks, local groups, governments. Can this cooperation be based on common values and on common languages? We argue that this is not always the case, that whenever there are unresolved ecological conflicts, there is likely to be not only a discrepancy but incommensurability in valuation (Faucheux and O’Connor, 1998, Funtowicz and Ravetz, 1994, Martinez-Alier, Munda and O’Neill, 1998, 1999, Martinez-Alier and O’Connor, 1996, 1999, O’Connor and Spash, 1999). Environmental conflicts are 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 22 expressed as conflicts on valuation, either inside one single standard of valuation, or across plural values. In other words, “semiotic resistance” (O’Connor, 1993; Escobar, 1996:61) to environmental abuse may be expressed in many languages. To see in statements about human rights, indigenous rights, sacredness, culture, livelihood, a lack of understanding or an a priori refusal of the techniques of economic valuation in actual or fictitious markets, indicates a failure to grasp the existence of value pluralism. Different interests can be defended either by insisting on the discrepancies of valuation inside the same standard of value, or by resorting to non-equivalent descriptions of reality, i.e. to different value standards. Should legislation require dispersed minerals to be concentrated again to their previous state and the dispersed overburden to be restored, this would indeed change the pattern of prices in the economy. Beyond economic values, choices on the use of “natural capital” involve decisions about which interests and forms of life will be sustained, which will be sacrificed or abandoned. A common language of valuation is not available for such decisions. For instance, it can be stated that while humans have different economic values they all have the same value in the scale of human dignity. When we say that someone or something is “very valuable” or “not very valuable”, this is an elliptical statement (which requires the further question, in which standard of valuation? (O’Neill, 1993). For policy, what is needed is not cost-benefit analysis but rather a non-compensatory multi-criteria approach able to accommodate a plurality of incommensurable values (Munda, 1995, Martinez-Alier, Munda and O’Neill, 1998, 1999). While conventional economics looks at environmental impacts in terms of externalities which should be internalized into the price system, one can see externalities (following Kapp) not as market failures but as cost-shifting successes which nevertheless might give rise to environmental movements (Leff. 1986,O’Connor, 1988). Such movements will legitimately employ a variety of vocabularies and strategies of resistance, and they cannot be gagged by cost-benefit analysis or by the cost-effectiveness approach. In conclusion, conflicts on the access to natural resources or on the exposure to environmental burdens and risks, may be expressed: : Inside one single standard of valuation. How should the externalities caused by a firm be valued in money terms, when demanding compensation in a court case? How could an argument for conservation of a natural space be made or contested, in terms of the number and biological value of the species it contains, or in terms of its net primary production? An appeal to the particular experts is here appropriate. : Through a value standard contest or dispute, that is a class in the standards of value to be applied, as when losses of biodiversity, or in cultural patrimony, or damage to human livelihoods, or infringements on human rights, are compared in non- 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 23 commensurable terms to economic gains from a new dam or from a mining project or from oil extraction. There is a clash in standards of valuation when the languages of environmental justice, or indigenous territorial rights, or environmental security, are deployed against monetary valuation of environmental risks and burdens. Non- compensatory multi-criteria decision aids or participatory methods of conflict resolution are more appropriate for this second, common type of situation, than the mere appeal to the disciplinary experts. (O’Connor and Spash, 1999:5). Thus, ecological distribution conflicts are sometimes expressed as discrepancies of valuation inside one single standard of value (as when there is a disputed claim for monetary compensation for an environmental liability), but they often lead to multi- criteria disputes (or dialogues) which rest on different standards of valuation. Which is “the price of oil”?- asked Human Rights Watch in a report on the Niger Delta. Todo necio/ confunde valor y precio - agreed long ago Antonio Machado. ENDNOTES 1 Butte has been known as the “richest hill on Earth” in Montana local lore and history, an honor which belongs not to Butte’s copper but to Potosi’s Cerro Rico’s silver. Butte recently “has earned the more dubious distinction of being the Environmental Protection Agency’s geographically largest “Superfund” cleanup site, a legacy of mining history” (Finn, 1998: 250, fn. 8). Butte used to belong to the Anaconda Company, which bought from Guggenheim the Chuquicamata mine in Chile, possibly the largest copper mine on earth. No Superfund for Chuquicamata, nor for Potosi. 2 Ferrero (1993:214) lists the articles of the Criminal Code which were infringed. There were no judicial pursuits in Spain or in Britain. 3 Skeptics also point out correctly that in Aznalcollar, a village inside the polluted area of 1888, the miners of Bolliden clamored in 1999 for “their” mine to reopen, against middle-class environmentalists from Seville and Madrid. Bolliden is a Swedish- Canadian company whose tailings dike broke down in 1998 contaminating with heavy metals ten thousand hectares of irrigated agriculture (where cultivation has been discontinued), and threatening the Doñana national park in the delta of the Guadalquivir. 4 Accion Ecologica (Quito) and Observatorio Latinoamericano de Conflictos Ambientales (Santiago de Chile), A los mineros: ni un paso atras en Junin-Intag, Quito, 1999. (On the wayno music, p.66). 5 Much of the documentation on this case comes from the files from the Permanent People’s Tribunal on Global Corporations and Human Wrongs organized by the Lelio Basso Foundation at the School of Law, University of Warwick, Coventry, 22-25 March 2000. See also Eyal Press, “Freeport-McMoRan at Home and Abroad”, The Nation, July 31-August 7, 1995, and Robert Bryce (from the newspaper Austin Chronicle), “Spinning Gold”, Mother Jones, Sept.- Oct. 1996.. 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 24 6 Mining Journal (London), vol. 329, n. 8448, 26 Sept. 1997. 7 Survival for Tribal Peoples (London), Media Briefing May 1998, “Rio Tinto critic gagged”. 8 I would myself frame the issue in terms of incommensurableness of values rather than the value being larger or smaller. 9 The Economist, 12 July 1997, p. 30. El Universal (Caracas), 3 August 1997, p. 1-12. 10 “Horinkhola and the surrounding villages have been declared a “Shrimp-Free Zone”, and every November 7, thousands of landless peasants gather here in a show of solidarity with this community’s resistance against the shrimp industry” (Ahmed, 1997:15). 11 R. Bullard, Directory. People of Color Environmental Groups 1994-1995, Environmental Justice Resource Center, Clark Atlanta University, Georgia. My underlining. 12 Available at www.saep.org, letter from Norton Tennille and Boyce W. Papu to Peter Mandelson, 7 September 1998. 13 Ronnie Morris, “UK court demolishes double standards”, Business Report, 4 March 1999, and subsequent information downloaded from www.saep.org. A UN report stated in 1990 that the Rossing uranium mine in Namibia was “a theft under the law and must be accounted for when Namibia becomes independent”. 14 Internal World Bank memo, as reported in The Economist, 8 February 1992, under the title “Let them eat pollution”. This has become a favorite text for the Environmental Justice movement. 15 Orlando Ochoa Teran, Quinto Dia, 18 January 2000, relayed by J.C.Centeno through the Environment in Latin America discussion list (ELAN at CSF). Some of us have been struggling for years to introduce the equivalent expression deuda ecologica. 16 Danilo Torres Ferrari, Los avances de la normativa sobre Cierre de Faenas Mineras, Boletin Minero (Chile), 1122, June 1999. 17 Deborah Robinson, International Possibilities Unlimited, Washington DC, “Environmental Devastation and Home & Abroad: The Importance of Understanding the Link”, 1999, www.preamble.org/environmental_justice REFERENCES Adeola, F O (2000) ‘Cross-National Environmental Injustice and Human Rights’, American Behavioral Scientist, 43(4), pp686-706 Agarwal, A and Narain, S (1991) Global warming: a case of environmental colonialism, Centre for Science and Environment, Delhi Ahmed, F (1997) In Defence of Land and Livelihood. Coastal Communities and the Shrimp Industry in Asia, Consumers’ Association of Penang, CUSO, InterPares, Sierra Club of Canada, Ottawa and Penang Amery, D (1974) Not on Queen Victoria’s birthday. The story of the Rio Tinto mines, 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 25 Collins, London Anderson, M R (1996) ‘The conquest of smoke: legislation and pollution in colonial Calcutta’ in Arnold, D and Guha, R (eds) Nature, Culture and Imperialism: Essays on the Environmental History of South Asia, Oxford U.P., Delhi, pp293-335 Arnold, D and Guha, R (eds) (1996) Nature, Culture and Imperialism: Essays on the Environmental History of South Asia, Oxford U.P., Delhi Balvin, D, Tejada Huaman, J and Lozada Coastro, H (1995) Agua, mineria y contaminacion. El caso Southern Peru, Labor, Ilo Barham, B, Bunker, S G and O’Hearn, D (1994) States, Firms and Raw Materials. The World Economy and Ecology of Aluminum, Univ. of Wisconsin Press, Madison Baviskar, A (1995) In the belly of the river: tribal conflict over development in the Narmada valley, Oxford U.P., Delhi Beckenbach, F (1996) ‘Ecological and economic distribution as elements of the evolution of modern societies’, Journal of Income Distribution, 6(2), pp163-91 Beinart, W and Coates, P (1995) Environment and History. The taming of Nature in the USA and South Africa, Routledge, London and New York Bond, P (2000) ‘Economic growth, ecological modernization or environmental justice? Conflicting discourses in post-apartheid South Africa’, Capitalism, Nature, Socialism, 11(1), pp33-61 Broadbent, J (1998) Environmental politics in Japan: networks of power and protest, Cambridge U.P., New York Brosius, J P (1999) ‘Comments to A. Escobar, After Nature: steps to an anti- essentialist political ecology’, Current Anthropology, 40(1) de Bruyn S M and Opschoor J B (1997) ‘Developments in the throughput-income relationship: theoretical and empirical observations’, Ecological Economics 20, pp255-68 Bryant, B and Mohai, P (eds) Race and the incidence of environmental hazards, Westview, Boulder Bryant, B (ed) (1995) Environmental Justice. Issues, Policies and Solutions, Island Press, Washington DC 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 26 Bryant, R and Bailey, S (eds) (1997) Third World Political Ecology, Routledge, London Bullard, R (1990) Dumping in Dixie: race, class and environmental quality, Westview, Boulder Bullard, R (1993) Confronting environmental racism. Voices from the grassroots, South End Press, Boston Bunker S (1996) ‘Raw materials and the global economy: oversights and distortions in industrial ecology’, Society and Natural Resources, 9, pp419-29 Camacho, D E (ed) Environmental Injustices, Political Struggles. Race, Class and the Environment, Duke University Press, Durham and London Carrere, R and Lohman, L (1996) Pulping the South. Industrial tree plantations and the world paper economy, Zed, London Cleveland, C and Ruth, M (1998) ‘Indicators of dematerialization and the materials intensity of use’, Journal of Industrial Ecology, 2, pp15-50 Cock, J and Koch, E (eds) (1991) Going Green: People, Politics and the Environment in South Africa, Oxford U.P., Cape Town Costanza, R (ed) (1991) Ecological economics: the science and management of sustainability. Columbia Univ Press, New York Dembo, D, Morehouse, W and Wykle, L (1990) Abuse of Power. Social Performance of Multinational Corporations: the Case of Union Carbide, New Horizons Press, New York Diaz Palacios, J (1988) El Peru y su medio ambiente. Southern Peru Copper Corporation: una compleja agresion ambiental en el sur del pais, IDMA, Lima DiChiro, G (1998), ‘Nature as Community. The Convergence of Environmental and Social Justice’ in Goldman, M (ed) Privatizing Nature: political struggles for the global commons, Pluto, London Dobson, A (1998) Justice and the environment. Conceptions of environmental sustainability and dimensions of social justice. Oxford U.P, Oxford Dore, E (2000) ‘Environment and Society: Long-term Trends in Latin American Mining’, Environment and History, 6, pp1-29 (previous version in Spanish in Ecologia Politica, 7, 1994) 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 27 Dorsey, M (1997) ‘El movimiento por la Justicia Ambiental en EE.UU. Una breve historia’, Ecologia Politica, 14, pp23-32 Downs, A (1972), ‘Up and Down with Ecology: the issue-attention cycle’, Public Interest, 28 Summer Draisma, T (1997) Mining and ecological degradation in Zambia: who bears the brunt when privatization clashes with Rio 1992?, Environmental Justice and Global Ethics Conference, Melbourne, October (revised version, August 1998) Dryzeck, J S (1994) ‘Ecology and discursive democracy: beyond liberal capitalism and the administrative state’ in O’Connor, M (ed) Is capitalism sustainable?, Guildford, New York Ekins, P, Max-Neef, M (eds) (1992) Real-life economics. Understanding wealth creation, Routledge, London Epstein, B (2000) ‘Grassroots environmentalism and strategies for social change’, New Social Movements Network, updated 28 February. 2000, http://www.interweb- tech.com/nsmnet/docs/epstein.htm Erickson, J D and Chapman, D (1993) ‘Sovereignty for Sale. Nuclear waste in Indian country’, Akwe:kon Journal, Fall, pp3-10. Erickson, J D, Chapman, D and Johny, R E (1994) ‘Monitored retrievable storage of spent nuclear fuel in Indian country: liability, sovereignty, and socioeconomics’, American Indian Law Review, University of Oklahoma College of Law, pp73-103 Escobar, A (1996) ‘Constructing Nature. Elements for a post-structural political ecology’ in Peet, R and Watts, M (eds) Liberation ecologies, Routledge, London Faber, D (ed) (1998) The struggle for ecological democracy. The Environmental Justice movement in the United States, Guildford, New York Faucheux, S and O’Connor, M (eds) (1998) Valuation for Sustainable Development. Methods and Policy Indicators, Edgar Elgar, Cheltenham Ferrero Blanco, M D (1994) Capitalismo minero y resistencia rural en el suroeste andaluz. Rio Tinto 1873-1900, Diputacion Provincial, Huelva Finn, J L (1998) Tracing the veins. Of copper, culture and community from Butte to Chuquicamata, University of California Press, Berkeley 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 28 Friedman, J and Rangan, H (eds) (1993) In Defense of Livelihood. Comparative Studies in Environmental Action, UNRISD, Kumarian Press, Hartford CT Funtowicz, S and Ravetz, J (1991) ‘A new scientific methodology for global environmental issues’ in Costanza, R (ed) Ecological economics: the science and management of sustainability. Columbia Univ Press, New York Funtowicz, S and Ravetz, J (1994) ‘The worth of a songbird: ecological economics as a post-normal science’, Ecological Economics, 10(3), pp189-96 Gadgil, M and Guha, R (1995) Ecology and equity. The use and abuse of nature in contemporary India, Routledge, London Garcia Rey, J (1996) ‘Nerva: No al vertedero. Historia de un pueblo en lucha’, Ecologia Politica, 13 Gedicks, A (1993) The new resource wars. Native and environmental struggles against multinational corporations, South End Press, Boston Ghai, D and Vivian, J M (eds) (1992) Grassroots environmental action. People’s participation in sustainable development, Routledge, London Gibbs, L M (1981) Love Canal: my story, State University of New York Press, Albany Gibbs, L M (1995) Dying from dioxin: a citizen’s guide to reclaiming our health and rebuilding democracy, South End Press, Boston Goldman, M (ed) (1998) Privatizing Nature: political struggles for the global commons, Pluto, London Gottlieb, R (1993) Forcing the spring: the transformation of the American environmental movement, Island Press, Washington DC Gould, K A, Schnaiberg, A and Weinberg, A (1996) Local environmental struggles. Citizen activism in the treadmill of production, Cambridge U.P., New York Greenpeace (1988) International Trade in Toxic Waste, Greenpeace, Brussels Greenpeace (1994) The database of known hazardous waste exports from OECD to non-OECD countries, 1989-94, Greenpeace, Washington DC Guha, R (1989) The unquiet woods: ecological change and peasant resistance in the Himalaya, University of California Press, Berkeley (revised edition 1999) 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 29 Guha, R and Martinez-Alier, J (1997) Varieties of environmentalism. Essays North and South, Earthscan, London Guha, R and Martinez-Alier, J (1999) ‘Political Ecology, the Environmentalism of the Poor, and the Global Movement for Environmental Justice’, Kurswechsel (Vienna), Heft 3, pp27-40 Hays, S (1959) Conservation and the Gospel of Efficiency. The Progressive Conservation Movement 1898-1929, Harvard U.P., Cambridge Hays, S (1998) Explorations in Environmental History, University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh Hecht, S and Cockburn, A (1990) The fate of the forest: developers, destroyers and defenders of the Amazon, Penguin, London Hofrichter, R (ed) (1993) Toxic Struggles. The Theory and Practice of Environmental Justice, New Society Publishers, Philadelphia Hornborg, A (1998) ‘Toward an ecological theory of unequal exchange: articulating world system theory and ecological economics’, Ecological Economics, 25(1), pp127- 136 Human Rights Watch (1999) The Price of Oil: Corporate Responsibility and Human Rights Violations in Nigeria’s Oil Producing Communities Human Rights Watch (1999) Toxic Justice: Human Rights, Justice and Toxic Waste in Cambodia Jackson, T and Marks, N (1999) ‘Consumption, sustainable welfare, and human needs - with reference to UK expenditure patterns between 1954 and 1994’, Ecological Economics, 28, pp421-441 Keil, R et al. (eds) (1998) Political ecology. Global and local, Routledge, London Kuletz, V (1998) The tainted desert. Environmental and social ruin in the American West, Routledge, New York Kurien, J (1992) ‘Ruining the commons and responses of the commoners: coastal overfishing and fishworkers’ actions in Kerala state, India’ in Ghai, D and Vivian, J M (eds) Grassroots environmental action. People’s participation in sustainable development, Routledge, London, pp221-258 Leff, E (1995) Green Production. Toward an environmental rationality, Guilford, 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 30 New York Lipman, Z (1998) ‘Trade in hazardous waste: environmental justice versus economic growth’, Conference on Environmental Justice, Melbourne, http//www.spartan.unimelb.edu.au/envjust/papers Lohman, L (1991) ‘Peasants, Plantations and Pulp: the Politics of Eucalyptus in Thailand’, Bulletin of Concerned Asian Scholars, 23(4) Lohman, L (1996) ‘Freedom to plant. Indonesia and Thailand in a globalizing pulp and paper industry’ in Parnwell, M J G and Bryant, R L (eds) Environmental Change in South-East Asia. People, Politics and Sustainable Development, Routledge, London and New York Low, N and Gleeson, B (1998) Justice, Society and Nature. An exploration of political ecology, Routledge, London and New York Mallon, F (1983) The defense of community in Peru’s Central Highlands, Princeton U.P., Princeton Martinez-Alier, J (1991) ‘Ecology and the poor: a neglected issue in Latin American history’, Journal of Latin American Studies, 23(3), pp621-640 Martinez-Alier J and Hershberg, E (1992) ‘Environmentalism and the poor’, Items, 46(1) March, Social Sciences Research Council, New York Martinez-Alier, J (1995) ‘Political ecology, distributional conflicts, and economic incommensurability’, New Left Review, 211 Martinez-Alier J and O’Connor, M (1996) ‘Ecological and economic distribution conflicts’ in Costanza, R, Segura, O and Martinez-Alier, J (eds) Getting down to earth: practical applications of ecological economics, ISEE, Island Press, Washington DC Martinez-Alier J and O’Connor, M (1999) ‘Distributional issues: an overview’ in Van den Bergh, J (ed). Handbook of Environmental and Resource Economics, Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, chapter 25 Martinez-Alier, J, Munda, G and O’Neill, J (1998) ‘Weak comparability of values as a foundation for ecological economics’, Ecological Economics, 26, pp277-286 Martinez-Alier, J, Munda, G and O’Neill, J (1999) ‘Commensurability and compensability in ecological economics’ in O’Connor, M and Spash, C (eds) Valuation and the environment. Theory, methods and practice. Edward Elgar, 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 31 Cheltenham McCully, P (1996) Silenced rivers. The ecology and politics of large dams, Zed, London McDonald, D (ed) (2000) Environmental Justice in South Africa, James Currey, London McNeill, J R (2000) Something new under the sun. An environmental history of the twentieth-century world, Norton, New York Mezger, D (1980) Copper in the world economy, Heineman, London Mikesell, R F (1988) The global copper industry, Croom Helm, London Mol, A (1995) The refinement of production: ecological modernization theory and the chemical industry, Van Arkel, Utrecht Mol, A (1997) ‘Ecological modernization: industrial transformation and environmental reform’ in Redclift, M and Woodgate, G (eds) The International Handbook of Environmental Sociology, Edward Elgar, Cheltenham Morehouse, W and Subramanian, M A (1986) The Bhopal Tragedy. What really happened and what it means for American workers and communities at risk, A preliminary report for the Citizens Commission on Bhopal, Council on International and Public Affairs, New York Moody, R (1992) The Gulliver File. Mines, people, and land: a global battleground, Minewatch-WISE-Pluto Press, London Munda, G (1995) Multicriteria evaluation in a fuzzy environment. Theory and applications in ecological economics, Physika Verlag, Heidelberg Naredo, J M and Valero, A (1999) Desarrollo economico y deterioro ecologico, Argentaria-Visor, Madrid Nimura, K (1997) The Ashio Riot of 1907. A Social History of Mining in Japan, Duke U.P., Durham and London Norgaard, R B. (1990) ‘Economic indicators of resource scarcity. A critical essay’, Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, 19, pp19-25 Novotny, P (1998) ‘Popular epidemiology and the struggle for community health in the environmental justice movement’ in Faber, D (ed) The struggle for ecological 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 32 democracy. The Environmental Justice movement in the United States, Guildford, New York, chapter 5 O’Connor, J (1988) ‘Introduction’, Capitalism, Nature, Socialism, 1 O’Connor, M (1993) ‘On the misadventures of capitalist nature’, Capitalism, Nature, Socialism, vol 4 (3), pp7-40 O’Connor, M (ed) (1996) ‘Ecological Distribution’, special issue of the Journal of Income Distribution, 6(2) O’Connor, M and Spash, C (eds) (1999) Valuation and the environment. Theory, methods and practice, Edward Elgar, Cheltenham O’Neill, J (1993) Ecology, policy and politics, Routledge, London Opschoor, J B (1995) ‘Ecospace and the fall and rise of throughput intensity’, Ecological Economics, 15(2), pp137-140 Painter, M and Durham, W (eds) (1995) The social causes of environmental destruction in Latin America, University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor Parikh, J K (1995) ‘Joint Implementation and the North and South Cooperation for Climate Change’, International Environmental Affairs. A Journal for Research and Policy, 7(1), pp22-41 Peet, R and Watts, M (eds) (1996) Liberation ecologies, Routledge, London Princen, T (1999) ‘Consumption and environment: some conceptual issues’, Ecological Economics, 3, pp347-363 Pulido, L (1996) Environmentalism and economic justice: two Chicano struggles in the Southwest, University of Arizona Press, Tucson Robleto, M L and Marcelo, W (1992) Deuda ecologica, Instituto de Ecologia Politica, Santiago, Chile Rocheleau, D. et al. (eds) (1995) Feminist political ecology, Routledge, London Sachs, A (1995) Eco-justice: linking human rights and the environment, Worldwatch Inst., Washington DC Saro-Wiwa, K (1995) A month and a day: a detention diary, Penguin, London 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 33 Schnaiberg, A et al. (1986) Distributional conflicts in environmental resource policy, Edward Elgar, Aldershot Schwab, J (1994) Deeper shades of green: the rise of blue-collar and minority of environmentalism in America, Sierra Club Books, San Francisco Shabecoff, P (2000) Earth Rising. American Environmentalism in the 21st Century, Island Press, Washington D.C. Strong, K (1977) Ox against the Storm. A biography of Tanaka Shozo: Japan’s conservationist pioneer, Paul Norbury, Tenterden, Kent Stroup, R L (1997) ‘Superfund: the shortcut that failed’ in Anderson, T L (ed) Breaking the environmental policy gridlock, Hoover Institution Press, Stanford Szasz, A (1994) Ecopopulism: toxic waste and the movement for environmental justice, University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis Tamanoi, Y, Tsuchida, A and Murota, T (1984) ‘Towards an entropic theory of economy and ecology - beyond the mechanistic equilibrium approach’, Economie apliquee, 37, pp279-94 Taylor, B R (ed) (1995) Ecological resistance movements. The global emergence of radical and popular environmentalism, SUNY Press, Albany Taylor, D (2000) ‘The Rise of the Environmental Justice Paradigm’, American Behavioral Scientist, 43(4) January Wapner, P (1996) Environmental activism and world civic politics, State University of New York Press, Albany Wargo, J (1996) Our Children’s Toxic Legacy. How Science and Law fail to protect us from Pesticides, Yale University Press, New Haven and London Von Weizsäcker, E, Lovins, A B and Lovins, L H (1997) Factor Four: doubling wealth, halving resource use (the new report to the Club of Rome), Earthscan, London Wenz, P (1988) Environmental Justice, State University of New York, Albany Westra, L and Wenz, P (1995) Faces of environmental racism: confronting issues of global justice, Rowman and Littlefield, Lanham MD World Resources Institute, Wuppertal Institut et al. (1997) Resources Flow: the material basis of industrial economies, World Resources Institute, Washington DC 3/2001-UHE/UAB-16/05/2001 34 work_7xesbovpavfvlcyfvkwzlbloty ---- No Job Name E D I T O R I A L : E C O N O M I C L I B E R A L I S M A N D S O C I A L J U S T I C E ecaf_1965 2..5 John Meadowcroft and Gerard Casey Introduction Economic liberalism and social justice have a somewhat paradoxical relationship: economic liberals tend to be extremely critical of the notion of social justice, yet economic liberalism has enabled the realisation of many of the goals of those who advocate social justice. The liberal institutions of free markets, the rule of law and secure private property rights have been the most successful mechanisms for the eradication of poverty and the empowerment of individual men and women that have ever been discovered. By contrast, attempts to deliberately achieve social justice have led to the immiserisation and disempowerment of many millions of people. Social justice as an intellectual error The classical liberal or libertarian critique of social or distributive justice begins by highlighting the fact that the very idea of social or distributive justice implies a deliberate allocation of resources. It implies that someone or some group has deliberately decided what income and wealth each individual or family should receive and that outcome can then be evaluated as either just or unjust. In the words of Nozick (1974, p. 149): ‘Hearing the term “distribution”, most people presume that some thing or mechanism uses some principle or criterion to give out a supply of things’, and that, ‘Into this process of distributing shares some error may have crept’. Hence, the concept of social justice would seem to demand that a faulty distribution of resources is corrected by deliberate intervention. The error of this analysis, however, is that in a market economy, ‘we are not in the position of children who have been given portions of pie by someone who now makes last minute adjustments to rectify careless cutting’ (Nozick, 1974, p. 149). The resources that would be reallocated in the name of social justice are not manna from heaven that could be divided in any number of ways between any number of people (although if such resources really were manna from heaven then some deliberative process for fairly distributing them would surely be appropriate). In reality, the resources that exist in a market economy are holdings that particular individuals are entitled to possess as a result of their actions in the creation of wealth and the exchange of goods and services. Hence, in the memorable words of Anthony de Jasay, one of the contributors to this symposium, social or distributive justice involves ‘slicing the cake nobody baked’ (de Jasay, 2002, p. 186). For classical liberals, then, the notion of social justice is first and foremost an intellectual error – a misunderstanding of how the world works. Indeed, Hayek (1976, pp. 62–63) argued that the demand for social or distributive justice is an example of anthropomorphism, the attribution of conscious intelligence to self-ordering, spontaneous processes that are in fact beyond conscious control. Social justice contra individual liberty Not only is the notion of social justice fundamentally flawed, classical liberals argue that attempts to realise social justice inevitably infringe people’s basic rights and destroy the wealth that is to be redistributed. The incompatibility of social justice and rights, or material equality and liberty, was famously illustrated by Nozick’s (1974, pp. 160–164) account of the wealth acquired by the basketball player Wilt Chamberlain in a fictional scenario. Taking as a starting point a distribution of resources that is considered just (which can be any distribution that the reader happens to prefer), Nozick supposes that the basketball player Wilt Chamberlain signs a contract in which each spectator who watches him play pays a special fee of 25 cents directly to Chamberlain (in addition to the standard ticket price). The fans are happy to pay the extra fee – watching Chamberlain play is worth more to them than 25 cents. Economic liberalism and social justice © 2010 The Authors. Journal compilation © Institute of Economic Affairs 2010. Published by Blackwell Publishing, Oxford Supposing that one million people come through the turnstiles during the course of a season, Chamberlain acquires additional personal wealth of $250,000. As a consequence of many small and seemingly inconsequential exchanges, then, one individual has amassed a sizeable personal fortune and a new distribution of resources has emerged. Nozick (1974, pp. 161–164) argues that this new distribution of resources must be considered just because it meets the criteria of ‘justice in acquisition’ and ‘justice in transfer’. The theoretical starting point of Nozick’s example was a distribution of resources that was considered just and from that point people voluntarily transferred their justly-held resources to Chamberlain in return for a service (watching him play) that they considered more valuable than the 25 cents each paid. In neither case can an injustice be said to have occurred, therefore the outcome of the transactions described must logically be considered just. Nozick’s example of Wilt Chamberlain’s acquisition of wealth illustrates how ‘liberty upsets patterns [of distribution]’ and inevitably produces inequalities (Nozick, 1974, p. 160; see also Hayek, 1960, p. 85). Where people are allowed to make free choices as to how they use their resources, deviations from any preferred pattern of distribution will inevitably arise. Any attempt to achieve a ‘just’ distribution of income and wealth must encounter the problem that countless transactions like those engaged in by Chamberlain and the basketball fans will take place and upset the ‘just’ distribution. Hence, the only way for social justice to be achieved is to forbid what Nozick calls ‘capitalist acts between consenting adults’ (Nozick, 1974, p. 163). In other words, social or distributive justice can only be attained where people are forbidden from producing and consuming, buying and selling, as they wish. For this reason, social justice and the basic rights inherent to a free society are judged to be incompatible. Social justice contra wealth creation Attempts to create a ‘just’ distribution of resources not only infringe people’s liberties, they also destroy the wealth that is to be deliberately distributed. Redistributing resources from those who engage in productive activity to those who do not engage in productive activity removes the incentives to wealth creation and the efficient use of resources. As Buchanan (1997, p. 360) has written, ‘Persons will care for, maintain and direct the use of productive resources properly only if there is a reciprocal relationship between effort expended and reward anticipated’. Actions that distort the relationship between effort and reward remove the incentive to undertake such efforts that might bring individual reward and contribute value to the wider society. Furthermore, the deliberate redistribution of resources distorts the information that is communicated by price signals in a market economy. As has been set out many times (for example Hayek, 1948; Mises, 1951), in a market economy prices provide knowledge of the relative costs and benefits of different courses of action. Without market prices it is impossible to arrive at an accurate relative valuation of the many millions of different goods and services that may be provided, and the many millions of different factors of production that may be used to create those goods and services. Such a monumental feat is beyond the comprehension of any single mind, group of minds working together, or even a super-computer, because the relevant knowledge is not only highly complex but is also inherently subjective, dispersed throughout the economy and frequently tacit. When prices are distorted by the deliberate allocation of income and wealth to particular individuals or groups, prices no longer correspond to people’s relative valuations of different goods and services and this prevents price signals from performing this essential co-ordinating function. Consequently, an economy in which price signals bear little relation to the relative values that people attach to different goods and services will be unable to efficiently allocate resources between different uses and over time the population will become relatively impoverished (Hayek, 1976, Ch. 3; Meadowcroft, 2005, Chs. 2 and 3). These are the underlying reasons why socialist and social democratic economies tend to be less efficient than market economies and therefore why attempts to achieve social justice tend to impoverish and disempower the very people such policies are intended to help. Hence, if our aim is to ameliorate poverty and empower the least advantaged then a market economy is the most effective mechanism for so doing. Social justice and economic liberalism These are the issues engaged with by the authors of the articles in this symposium. In the first article, Anthony de Jasay addresses the theoretical foundations of liberal justice and its corruption by supposedly liberal thinkers. Jasay draws a distinction between rules that emerge spontaneously because they are to people’s mutual advantage and laws that are deliberately imposed on society by those with political authority. Liberal justice is rooted in this first system of conventions that are ascertainable facts of history and anthropology, rather than government-made laws that by definition must have dubious lineage and therefore questionable legitimacy. Unfortunately, Jasay argues, this liberal order of rules and conventions has been undermined by many of its principal defenders. In particular, Jasay argues that Mill’s (1859) harm principle, Rawls’ theory of justice (1971) and Locke’s theory of property (1689) have all opened the way for the enemies of liberty to undermine the theoretical foundations of genuinely liberal justice, so that today people are deemed to be free to act only if their actions can be shown not to harm others (and almost any act can be judged to harm others), only if their actions can be shown to be within their explicitly stated rights (and such rights have been rendered meaningless by the extension of the notion of rights to include all manner of entitlements) and only if they utilise property the acquisition of which can be shown to have left enough and as good for others (and where resources are finite an individual’s possession of property can never leave enough and as good for others). Jasay argues that the institutionalisation of these erroneous ‘liberal’ ideas of justice in the modern democratic state centred upon government-made law has led to the emasculation of individual liberty in contemporary societies: there are almost 3iea e c o n o m i c a f f a i r s m a r c h 2 0 1 0 © 2010 The Authors. Journal compilation © Institute of Economic Affairs 2010. Published by Blackwell Publishing, Oxford no limits to the scope of collective choice and no means for the individual to protect their own private space from invasion by the state. Nevertheless, Jasay does offer some hope for a revival of liberal justice based upon conventions and rules given that contemporary democratic states were founded upon such rules and conventions; a restoration of freedom may still be possible if we are able to dig back to these foundations. Any liberal theory of justice that aspires to be comprehensive must engage with the question of restitution. Where it can be shown that property has been acquired illegitimately, perhaps over many generations, or many generations ago, then the long-term economic consequences of such wrongs must be addressed if the distribution of income and wealth in a given society is to be considered just. This is the challenge addressed by Karol Boudreaux of the Mercatus Center at George Mason University in her contribution to this symposium. Boudreaux’s article analyses restitution and economic liberalism in South Africa, a country with a long history of legislation that discriminated against the black majority of the population. Boudreaux examines the empirical example of the land reform legislation introduced in South Africa after the transition from apartheid in 1994. This legislation was in part a response to calls for greater social justice. Boudreaux cites evidence that suggests that the land reform legislation has had little impact in righting the wrongs of the past, largely because only the wealthy and well-connected have the necessary resources (broadly defined) to navigate the judicial process. By contrast, the operation of market forces has had a much more dramatic impact, leading to the diversification of land ownership patterns, encouraging economic growth and promoting rural economic development. As has been the experience in other places and at other times, it is market mechanisms, not government diktat, that are able to realise the goals of widespread empowerment and poverty alleviation. In the third article of the symposium, Thomas E. Woods Jr. of the Ludwig von Mises Institute focuses on two misconceptions that he believes have added significantly to the confusion surrounding the relationship of economics and morality. Advocates of social justice often take economics to task for failing to give ethics free play in their discipline. Moreover, it is often implied that by following their prescriptions, we could bring about a world in which there need not to be any trade-offs between various human demands, claiming, in effect, that we could have a world without scarcity. Woods argues that the first misconception involves a serious theoretical misunderstanding of the relation between the various sciences. Economics as a science, which is the study of the market and its operations, has no moral dimension, anymore than chemistry or physics as sciences have moral dimensions. This is not to say, as social justice proponents often appear to claim, that such a view of economics commits us to the thesis that the marketplace has no moral dimension. Of course it does. But the marketplace is one thing; the scientific study of the marketplace is another. The second misconception arises, Woods contends, from a failure on the part of some social justice advocates to grasp the fundamental economic point that we live in a world where scarcity is the norm. Even should every other resource be freely available, as mortal beings our time is an inherently scarce resource. An increase in the overall wealth of society, however desirable that may be, cannot be achieved just by wishing for it. The world doesn’t operate according to the laws of magic, and real wealth is a product of work applied to natural resources in the most productive manner. Sometimes, the proponents of social justice give the impression that all manner of things would be well if only we had a just system of distribution. But this is an example of the Garden-of-Eden fallacy which regards the world as a paradise in which all that we need or want is freely available. The burden of William Luckey’s article is to provide some suggestions for the construction of an authentic and authoritative body of Catholic doctrine on social and economic matters. He begins by criticising a certain approach to Church and Papal documents which is both selective and textually naïve and, more significantly, which attributes an authoritative status to those documents that they do not, as a whole, possess. Luckey is also critical of the attempt to collect and thematise the Social Teaching of the Church, as exemplified by the compilation of the Compendium of the Social Doctrine of the Church. As he points out, social teachings are not, just as such, a matter of the discernment of Revelation, but a prudential matter of applying ethical principles to concrete social and economic questions. While Catholics accept that the Church has authority in matters of faith and morals, it doesn’t follow from this that its prudential judgments are similarly authoritative nor, indeed, that the Church has any particular competence in technical or scientific matters. The elements of authentic Catholic social teaching should be based upon foundational Catholic moral theology and an adequate philosophical anthropology. Without a proper understanding of the human person, no social teaching can be developed. Man is a creature possessing reason and free will, albeit that his intellect is darkened and his will weakened. Human freedom has as its consequence the acceptance by man of his responsibility for his choices, including his economic choices and while respecting man’s freedom, the Church has a duty to give him moral guidance. Luckey contends that the implications of the Second Vatican Council’s Decree on Religious Freedom, Dignitatis Humanae, have not yet been adequately analysed and that this can be extended theologically to defend a free economy. Luckey concludes with a brief analysis of the latest Social Encyclical, Benedict XVI’s Caritas in Veritate, and claims that Pope Benedict’s thinking on these matters can be traced to a latter-day defender of the Romantic School of Economics. The final article in this symposium by Elaine Sternberg examines a recent argument for redistribution in the name of social justice. This argument, set out by Gar Alperovitz and Lew Daly in their recent book Unjust Deserts (2008), claims that since innovation depends far more on accumulated knowledge than on any single individual’s contribution, most of the resulting wealth is deserved equally by all members of society. It is an argument that implicitly invokes Nozick’s entitlement theory of justice but argues that because wealth creation depends in some sense on the contributions of 4 e c o n o m i c l i b e r a l i s m a n d s o c i a l j u s t i c e © 2010 The Authors. Journal compilation © Institute of Economic Affairs 2010. Published by Blackwell Publishing, Oxford countless people over untraceable time to the accumulated store of knowledge from which innovators then draw, such innovators cannot claim an entitlement to the wealth that is thereby created. In her article, Sternberg sets out Alperovitz’s and Daly’s argument and then exposes its fallacies and errors. First, Sternberg argues, Alperovitz and Daly apply the concept of distributive justice to a realm where such a concept does not logically apply. As noted above in this introduction, the distribution of income and wealth that exists in a market economy is not the result of a deliberate allocation by a central planner but is the result of the spontaneous operation of economic forces and hence cannot be properly considered either just or unjust. Second, Sternberg shows that Alperovitz’s and Daly’s claim that people have no right to that (for example, wealth) which they have not deliberately created is an unsubstantiated and ultimately dangerous claim which logically gives individuals no right over their own bodies (which they have not deliberately created) as well as their income and wealth. Third, Sternberg shows that Alperovitz and Daly have failed to properly take into account the role of individual freedom, individual achievement and free markets in the process of wealth creation that has benefited mankind during the last two centuries. Conclusion The articles in this symposium show that the outcomes produced by a free-market economy cannot logically be considered just or unjust, in the same way that the operation of any natural forces, such as weather patterns or the spread of a virus, are similarly neither just nor unjust. Rather, justice can only ever be procedural, concerning the neutral application of rules and/or conventions that establish the rule of law and protect private property rights (including people’s right to a property in their own person). Paradoxically, perhaps, it is nevertheless the operation of free markets within the context of the rule of law and the protection of private property rights that create the conditions for wealth creation on a societal scale that enables the alleviation of poverty and the empowerment of the poorest members of society. In this way, the goals of those who advocate social justice are more likely to be achieved via the free market than via any deliberate intervention. References Alperovitz, G. and L. Daly (2008) Unjust Deserts: How the Rich Are Taking Our Common Inheritance and Why We Should Take It Back; Wealth and Inequality in the Knowledge Economy, New York: The New Press. Buchanan, J. M. (1997 [2001]) ‘Reform without Romance: First Principles in Political Economy’, in Volume 19 of the Collected Works of James Buchanan: Ideas, Persons, and Events, Indianapolis: Liberty Fund. Hayek, F. A. (1948) ‘The Use of Knowledge in Society’, in Individualism and Economic Order, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Hayek, F. A. (1960) The Constitution of Liberty, London: Routledge. Hayek, F. A. (1976) The Mirage of Social Justice, London: Routledge. Jasay, A. de (2002) Justice and Its Surroundings, Indianapolis: Liberty Fund. Locke, J. (1689 [1993]) Two Treatises on Government, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Meadowcroft, J. (2005) The Ethics of the Market, Basingstoke: Palgrave. Mill, J. S. (1859 [1985]) On Liberty, London: Penguin Classics. Mises, L. von (1951 [1981]) Socialism, trans. J., Kahane, Indianapolis: Liberty Fund. Nozick, R. (1974) Anarchy, State, and Utopia, Oxford: Blackwell. Rawls, J. (1971) A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. John Meadowcroft is a Lecturer in Public Policy at King’s College London (john.meadowcroft@kcl.ac.uk). Gerard Casey is Associate Professor of Philosophy at University College Dublin (gerard.casey@ucd.ie). 5iea e c o n o m i c a f f a i r s m a r c h 2 0 1 0 © 2010 The Authors. Journal compilation © Institute of Economic Affairs 2010. Published by Blackwell Publishing, Oxford work_7y6s67igvrbxjigaelfsgvkqfq ---- COVID-19 and justice J Med Ethics October 2020 Vol 46 No 10 639 COVID-19 and justice John McMillan, Editor in Chief John Rawls begins a Theory of Justice with the observation that 'Justice is the first virtue of social institutions, as truth is of systems of thought… Each person possesses an inviolability founded on justice that even the welfare of society as a whole cannot override'1 (p.3). The COVID-19 pandemic has resulted in lock- downs, the restriction of liberties, debate about the right to refuse medical treatment and many other changes to the everyday behaviour of persons. The justice issues it raises are diverse, profound and will demand our attention for some time. How we can respect the Rawlsian commit- ment to the inviolability of each person, when the welfare of societies as a whole is under threat goes to the heart of some of the difficult ethical issues we face and are discussed in this issue of the Journal of Medical Ethics. The debate about ICU triage and COVID-19 is quite well developed and this journal has published several articles that explore aspects of this issue and how different places approach it.2–5 Newdick et al add to the legal analysis of triage deci- sions and criticise the calls for respecting a narrow conception of a legal right to treatment and more detailed national guidelines for how triage decisions should be made.6 They consider scoring systems for clin- ical frailty, organ failure assessment, and raise some doubts about the fairness of their application to COVID-19 triage situ- ations. Their argument seems to highlight instances of what is called the McNamara fallacy. US Secretary of Defense Robert McNamara used enemy body counts as a measure of military success during the Vietnam war. So, the fallacy occurs when we rely solely on considerations that appear to be quantifiable, to the neglect of vital qualitative, difficult to measure or contestable features.6 Newdick et al point to variation in assessment, subtlety in condition and other factors as reasons why it is misleading to present scoring systems as ‘objective’ tests for triage. In doing so they draw a distinction between procedural and outcome consistency, which is important, and hints at distinc- tions Rawls drew between the different forms of procedural fairness. While we might hope to come up with a triage protocol that is procedurally fair and arrives at a fair outcome (what Rawls calls perfect procedural justice, p. 85) there is little prospect of that. As they observe, reasonable people can disagree about the outcomes we should aim for in allo- cating health resources and ICU triage for COVID-19 is no exception. Instead, we should work toward a transparent and fair process, what Rawls would describe as imperfect procedural justice (p. 85). His example of this is a criminal trial where we adopt processes that we have reason to believe are our best chance of determining guilt, but which do not guarantee the truth of a verdict, and this is a reason why they must be transparent and consistent (p. 85). Their proposal is to triage patients into three broad categories: high, medium and low priority, with the thought that a range of considerations could feed into that evaluation by an appropriately constituted clinical group. Ballantyne et al question another issue that is central to the debate about COVID-19 triage.4 They describe how utility measures such as QALYs, lives saved seem to be in tension with equity. Their central point is that ICU for COVID-19 can be futile, and that is a reason for questioning how much weight should be given to equality of access to ICU for COVID-19. They claim that there is little point admitting someone to ICU when ICU is not in their best interests. Instead, the scope of equity should encom- pass preventing 'remediable differences among social, economic demographic or geographic groups' and for COVID-19 that means looking beyond access to ICU. Their central argument can be summarised as follows. 1. Maximising utility can entrench exist- ing health inequalities. 2. The majority of those ventilated for COVID-19 in ICU will die. 3. Admitting frailer or comorbid patients to ICU is likely to do more harm than good to these groups. 4. Therefore, better access to ICU is un- likely to promote health equity for these groups. 5. Equity for those with health inequal- ities related to COVID-19 should broadened to include all the services a system might provide. Brown et al argue in favour of COVID-19 immunity passports and the following summarises one of the key argu- ments in their article.7 1. COVID-19 immunity passports are a way of demonstrating low personal and social risk. 2. Those who are at low personal risk and low social risk from COVID-19 should be permitted more freedoms. 3. Permitting those with immunity pass- ports greater freedoms discriminates against those who do not have pass- ports. 4. Low personal and social risk and pre- serving health system capacity are rel- evant reasons to discriminate between those who have immunity and those who do not. Brown et al then consider a number of potential problems with immunity pass- ports, many of which are justice issues. Resentment by those who do not hold an immunity passport along with a loss of social cohesion, which is vital for responding to COVID-19, are possible downsides. There is also the potential to advantage those who are immune, economically, and it could perpetuate existing inequalities. A significant objection, which is a problem for the justice of many policies, is free riding. Some might create fraudulent immunity passports and it might even incentivise intentional exposure to the virus. Brown et al suggest that disin- centives and punishment are potential solu- tions and they are in good company as the Rawlsian solution to free riding is for 'law and government to correct the necessary corrections.' (p. 268) Elves and Herring focus on a set of ethical principles intended to guide those making policy and individual level deci- sions about adult social care delivery impacted by the pandemic.8 They criticize the British government’s framework for being silent about what to do in the face of conflict between principles. They suggest the dominant values in the framework are based on autonomy and individualism and argue that there are good reasons for not making autonomy paramount in policy about COVID-19. These include that infor- mation about COVID-19 is incomplete, so no one can be that informed on decisions about their health. The second is one that highlights the importance of viewing our present ethical challenges via the lens of justice or other ethical concepts such as community or solidarity that enable us to Concise argument doi:10.1136/medethics-2020-106877 o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://jm e .b m j.co m / J M e d E th ics: first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /m e d e th ics-2 0 2 0 -1 0 6 8 7 7 o n 2 3 S e p te m b e r 2 0 2 0 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://jme.bmj.com http://www.instituteofmedicalethics.org http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1136/medethics-2020-106877&domain=pdf&date_stamp=2020-09-15 http://jme.bmj.com/ 640 J Med Ethics October 2020 Vol 46 No 10 Concise argument frame collective obligations and interests. They observe that COVID-19 has demon- strated how health and how we live our lives are linked: that what an individual does can have profound impact on the health of many others. Their view is that appeals to self- determination ring hollow for COVID-19 and their proposed remedy is one that pushes us to reflect on what the liberal commitment to the inviolability of each person means. They explain Dworkin’s account of 'associative obligations' which occur within a group when they acknowl- edge special rights and responsibilities to each other. These obligations are a way of giving weight to community considerations, without collapsing into full- blown utilitari- anism and while still respecting the inviola- bility of persons. The COVID-19 pandemic is pushing ethical deliberation in new directions and many of them turn on approaching medical ethics with a greater emphasis on justice and related ethical concepts. Funding The authors have not declared a specific grant for this research from any funding agency in the public, commercial or not- for- profit sectors. Competing interests None declared. Patient consent for publication Not required. Provenance and peer review Commissioned; internally peer reviewed. This article is made freely available for use in accordance with BMJ’s website terms and conditions for the duration of the covid-19 pandemic or until otherwise determined by BMJ. You may use, download and print the article for any lawful, non- commercial purpose (including text and data mining) provided that all copyright notices and trade marks are retained. © Author(s) (or their employer(s)) 2020. No commercial re- use. See rights and permissions. Published by BMJ. REFERENCES 1 Rawls J. A theory of justice. Oxford University Press: Oxford, 1972. 2 Solnica A, Barski L, Jotkowitz A. Allocation of scarce resources during the COVID-19 pandemic: a Jewish ethical perspective. J Med Ethics 2020;46(7):444–6. 3 Herreros B, Gella P, Real de Asua D. Triage during the COVID-19 epidemic in Spain: better and worse ethical arguments. J Med Ethics 2020;46(7):455–8. 4 Ballantyne A, Rogers WA, Entwistle V, et al. Revisiting the equity debate in COVID-19: ICU is no panacea. J Med Ethics 2020;46:641–5. 5 Liddell K, Skopek JM, Palmer S, et al. Who gets the ventilator? Important legal rights in a pandemic. J Med Ethics 2020;46(7):421–6. 6 O’Mahony S. Medicine and the McNamara fallacy. J R Coll Physicians Edinb 2018;47(3):281–7. 7 Brown RCH, Savulescu J, Williams B, et al. Passport to freedom? immunity passports for COVID-19. J Med Ethics 2020;46:652–9. 8 Elves CB, Herring J. Ethical framework for adult social care in COVID-19. J Med Ethics 2020;46:662–7. o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://jm e .b m j.co m / J M e d E th ics: first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /m e d e th ics-2 0 2 0 -1 0 6 8 7 7 o n 2 3 S e p te m b e r 2 0 2 0 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://dx.doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2020-106242 http://dx.doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2020-106352 http://dx.doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2020-106460 http://dx.doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2020-106460 http://dx.doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2020-106332 http://dx.doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2020-106332 http://dx.doi.org/10.4997/JRCPE.2017.315 http://dx.doi.org/10.4997/JRCPE.2017.315 http://dx.doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2020-106365 http://dx.doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2020-106365 http://dx.doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2020-106513 http://jme.bmj.com/ COVID-19 and justice References work_a3zlvs7akjd3lh5y6ddmkftmpm ---- ”Social justice in a changing world“ Conference at the Graduate School of Social Sciences, University of Bremen, March 10–12, 2005 alle Interessenten, bis zum 08. Oktober 2004 Vorschläge für eigene Beiträge einzureichen. Die einseitigen Abstracts sollten per Mail an Jörg Hagenah hagenah@wiso.uni-koeln.de ge- schickt werden. Dabei können Vorschläge zu fol- genden Themenschwerpunkten eingereicht wer- den: Bedeutung der Media-Analyse: Potenziale für wissenschaftliche Sekundäranalysen; Medien- nutzung im Wandel der Zeit; Spezifische Formen der Mediennutzung; Sozialer Wandel und Ent- wicklungen des Konsum-/Freizeitverhaltens; Me- thodische Aspekte bei Sekundäranalysen. Geplant ist zudem ein offener Themenblock. Außerdem können Personen, die einen schnellen, intensiven Einblick in die Potenziale von Sekun- däranalysen mit den ma-Daten gewinnen wollen, als Zuhörer am Workshop teilnehmen. Der Ausrichter der Veranstaltung ist das Me- dienwissenschaftliche Lehr- und Forschungszen- trum der Wirtschafts- und Sozialwissenschaftli- chen Fakultät der Universität zu Köln. Veranstal- ter ist der Geschäftsführende Direktor des Zen- trums Prof. Dr. Heiner Meulemann mit seinen Mitarbeitern Dr. Jörg Hagenah und Haluk Akinci. Ausführlichere und aktualisierte Informatio- nen zum Workshop sind auf der Homepage des MLFZ zu finden: „http://www.wiso.uni-koeln.de/medien/“. ∗ “Social Justice in a Changing World” Conference at the Graduate School of Social Sciences, University of Bremen, March 10–12, 2005 A growing number of experts in economics, po- litical science and sociology believe that the free- dom of action of the nation-state in coping with issues of distributive justice is waning. Current processes of economic privatisation and globaliza- tion shift power over distribution from the state toward ‘capital’ and markets. What are the impli- cations for social justice? The conference will ex- plore the risks and options of privatised markets and transnational regimes for social justice on different levels. On the individual level, we expe- rience an increasing mismatch of individual life course risks like unemployment, poverty or mari- tal separation and state protection, and the emer- gence of new forms of social inequality. In this conference, we may address the distributional outcomes and developments of different social groups. Who are the winners and losers in times of globalization? What kind of social justice do people expect? On the domestic level, we witness the disintegration of the collective bargaining process, the scaling back of social insurance and the resulting bourgeoning of mixed and private forms of social provision. Does distributive jus- tice continue to be a central goal of welfare state activity? What could be the features of a new so- cial contract? On the international level, trade is the main area in which regulatory processes oc- cur. Transnational regimes increasingly constrain the environmental, agricultural, health and food safety rules of democratic constitutional states, and thus affect the fundamental welfare of citi- zens. How can social rights and distributive jus- tice be guaranteed in the international legal framework? What role do non-governmental ac- tors play in the regulatory processes? Can the rec- ognition of social rights open avenues towards ensuring the legitimacy of transnational gover- nance? The conference will consist of plenary ses- sions as well as of thematic panels for which we invite abstract submissions. The abstract deadline is November 30, 2004. The conference venue will be the Atlantic Hotel Bremen close to the campus of the University of Bremen. For more information on registration, panels, accommoda- tion etc. please visit the conference website: “www.gsss.uni-bremen.de/socialjustice”. ∗ „Medien – Identität – Identifikationen“ Tagung der Sektion Jugendsoziologie und der Sektion Medien- und Kommunikationssoziologie der DGS vom 25.–26.2.2005 an der Hochschule für Film und Fernsehen Potsdam-Babelsberg Die Aufgabe der Identitätsausbildung erfolgt im Wesentlichen durch die aktive, reflektierte Aus- einandersetzung des Individuums mit gesell- schaftlichen Erwartungen, kulturellen Kontexten und Traditionen. Dringlich ist die Identitätsar- beit insbesondere in der sensiblen Phase der Ado- leszenz. Ging man früher davon aus, dass sich Identität primär in personalen Interaktionen ent- wickelt, muss man zu Beginn des 21. Jahrhun- derts mediale Interaktionen einbeziehen. Den Medien kann geradezu eine „Schlüsselrolle in der Strukturierung von zeitgenössischer Identität“ (Douglas Kellner) attestiert werden. Die Beschäf- tigung mit dem Anderen und sich selbst findet nicht nur in interpersonalen Kontexten und in 602 Nachrichten und Mitteilungen work_a4g4x555wfe5xgkxfqw45k52oa ---- pme02659_prn 330..333 Preventive Medicine 49 (2009) 330–333 Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Preventive Medicine journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/ypmed Commentary “Pushing” physical activity, and justice Robert García a, America Bracho b, Patricia Cantero b, Beth A. Glenn c,⁎ a The City Project, Los Angeles, CA, USA b Latino Health Access, 1701 N. Main Street, Suite 200, Santa Ana, CA, USA c School of Public Health, and Jonsson Comprehensive Cancer Center, University of California, Los Angeles, 650 Charles Young Dr. South, Room A2-125, CHS, Los Angeles, CA 90095-6900, USA 0091-7435/$ – see front matter © 2009 Elsevier Inc. A doi:10.1016/j.ypmed.2009.07.016 ⁎ Corresponding author. Fax: +1 310 206 3566. E-mail address: bglenn@ucla.edu (B.A. Glenn). a b s t r a c t Objective. There has been an increasing realization of the need for environmental interventions to a r t i c l e i n f o Available online 29 July 2009 Keywords: Physical activity Obesity Fitness Racial or ethnic minority African American Black Latino Hispanic Disparities Civil rights Justice Built environment Education Law increase physical activity levels in the population. Although promising, the impact of these strategies in reducing obesity-related disparities will be limited by the presence of inequities in the distribution of activity-related resources in the community. Advocacy efforts are critically needed to ensure that all communities benefit from environmental strategies being implemented. Method and results. This paper describes two activist community-based organizations in Southern California, The City Project and Latino Health Access, and their successful efforts to mandate equitable access to public resources critical for reducing obesity-related disparities. Conclusion. Principles for equitable development of public land are also presented as well as lessons learned that can inform future advocacy efforts. © 2009 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. Introduction Increasing the availability of safe-space for physical activity (Babey et al., 2008), opportunities to engage in physical activity during the school day (Cawley et al., 2007), and access to and use of public trans- portation (Lachapelle and Frank, 2009) are environmental strategies that have been found to be related to increased physical activity levels. Low-income, ethnic minority families are less likely to have access to parks or other space for physical activity (Estabrooks et al., 2003), less likely to engage in physical activity during leisure time (Brown et al., 2005) and are more dependent on public transportation (Mather, 2009).Evidence isaccumulatingthat promotingmass transit use may be a promising strategy to increase physical activity levels (Lachapelle and Frank, 2009). However, low-income and minority communities, those most likely to need public transit and who may be more likely to benefit from its use from a physical activity standpoint often have poorest access to these resources. Thus, these environmental change approaches hold the promise of being particularly beneficial for socioeconomically marginalized groups. Therefore, we propose that efforts should be made to mandate the equitable distribution of public resources that will ultimately increase physical activity levels in the population. The purpose of this article is to propose steps that may be neces- sary to bring about population-wide increases in physical activity ll rights reserved. level and ultimately to reduce obesity-related disparities. California, the only “majority minority” state in the continental U.S. and a leader in health promotion, is host to a number of activist community-based organizations engaged in grassroots advocacy. Case studies of two such agencies, The City Project and Latino Health Access, are included to illustrate how these organizations have spearheaded efforts to mandate equitable access to public resources critical for reducing obesity-related disparities. Finally, we put forth principles of equitable development to guide others in their efforts to advocate for the health of their respective communities. Steps in public health advocacy First, there is a need to bring people together through coalition building and a shared vision based on diverse values. Grassroots engagement is a necessity, and may require the development of coalitions with broad agendas and working across multiple issues as has been noted by others (Tajik and Minkler, 2007). The composition and nature of the coalition that are likely to be successful will depend on the timeline for achieving the goal, characteristics of the affected community and the health topic of concern among other factors. Second, sophisticated analytic approaches and broad frameworks are needed when conducting research to understand the relationship between obesity and its multiple environmental determinants including the implications of laws and public policies as well as the built environment (Sacks et al., 2009). Health Impact Assessments can 331R. García et al. / Preventive Medicine 49 (2009) 330–333 be valuable tools in assessing both the intentional and unintentional effects of public policies and programs (Dannenberg et al., 2008). Community-based participatory research (CPBR) approaches should be used to ensure that results are meaningful to the community and provide the foundation for future advocacy efforts (Tajik and Minkler, 2007). CBPR methods can be used to systematically study the process of advocacy (e.g., assessing quality and nature of partnerships and coalitions) as well as the outcomes of advocacy efforts (e.g., im- provements in perceived and objective health). Evaluation of health outcomes is particularly important in ensuring that programs and policies that improve health are sustained. Third, strategic media campaigns can focus attention on the need for systemic change and increase your likelihood of success (Tajik and Minkler, 2007). Taking advantage of traditional media and new social media (including GIS mapping, blogs, flickr, YouTube, and podcasts) can lead to increased visibility and support for your cause. Fourth, taking advantage of available policy and legal advocacy resources outside the courts may be effective in persuading public officials to take action. For example, the Robert Wood Johnson Foundation-funded National Policy and Legal Action Network (NPLAN) provides legal and policy analyses as a national resource to policymakers and advocacy groups seeking to change physical activity and nutrition environments to address childhood obesity. Finally, access to justice through the courts is available as a last resort if all else fails in the context of an overall campaign (García and White, 2006). Lessons learned from tobacco litigation in the U.S. may have application to other areas, and indeed, many grassroots advocates “cut their teeth” on public health tobacco control efforts. The following case studies illustrate efforts undertaken by The City Project and Latino Health Access to ensure equitable access to public resources relevant to physical activity in Southern California. Case studies The City Project The City Project, located in Los Angeles, California, is a non-profit policy and legal problem solving organization whose work includes specific strategies to build healthy, livable communities for all, and principles for equitable development to achieve systemic change and real choice. In Los Angeles County, children of color and those living in poverty have the highest levels of obesity. These children also have the least access to parks, to schools with at least 5 acres of playing field, and to mass transit (García and White, 2006). Thus, the City Project has engaged in a number of initiatives that have laid the groundwork for reducing obesity disparities in the county and throughout California. Creation of safe-space for physical activity Activists and attorneys worked with the community through policy and legal advocacy to help create the forty-acre Rio de Los Angeles State Park on a former rail yard in one of the most park- starved communities in the region and stop a commercial project there. This is part of a broader campaign in what is now known as the Urban Park Movement to revitalize the 52-mile Los Angeles River (which was lined with concrete as flood control measure in the 1930s) with parks, schools, affordable housing, local green jobs, and multi-use green spaces that help clean the air and water and promote climate justice. The parks and school fields should provide places for physical activity to alleviate obesity and promote physical and mental health of the people (García and White, 2006). Ensuring opportunities for PA during school for low-income and minority children More than half of the public school districts in California do not enforce physical education requirements (California Center for Public Health Advocacy, 2006). In response, The City Project is working with the United Teachers of Los Angeles (the teachers' union) and others to enforce the physical education laws in the Los Angeles Unified School District, the second largest in the nation with more than 700,000 students—91% are children of color and 74% are low income. The teachers' union launched a physical education campaign to build public support among teachers, parents, students and the public. The City Project filed an administrative (Williams) complaint under civil rights and education laws. The board of education passed a resolu- tion to enforce the physical education and civil rights laws. Teachers, lawyers, and school officials are working together to draft a far- reaching plan to implement the resolution, enforce the law, and resolve the complaint. Each of these elements is based, in part, on evidence from studies investigating public school physical education inequities commissioned by The California Endowment (García and Fenwick, 2009). Increasing access to public transportation In 1994, lawyers and organizers working together filed a historic civil rights and environmental justice lawsuit against the Los Angeles County Metropolitan Transportation Agency (MTA) on the grounds that it operated separate and unequal bus and rail systems that discriminated against the working poor with little or no access to a car. MTA agreed to settle the case in 1996 and invested over $2 billion to improve transit throughout the county and keep fares low over the next ten years (García and Rubin, 2004). Latino Health Access Latino Health Access (LHA) is a non-profit public health organiza- tion founded in 1993. It assists in improving the quality of life of underserved Latino residents in Orange County, California. The majority of the services (66%) are provided to residents of Santa Ana, one of the poorest and densest cities in the state. LHA was one of the early innovators in the development of the Promotor (Community Health Worker) model of community outreach and health education. One of the focuses of LHA's work is creating an environmental change to support responsible personal and family food choices and physical activity participation. For example, as one of six Healthy Eating Active Communities sites in California, LHA engages the community, city officials, the Orange County Health Care Agency, and the Santa Ana Unified School District in discussions on wellness policies, often involving their youth Promotores in door-to-door outreach, hosting town hall meetings and forums, and testifying before school boards and city councils. LHA has been focused, for the past six years, on addressing the inequity in park distribution in Santa Ana. They partnered with Trust for Public Land to conduct a feasibility study demonstrating that Santa Ana has roughly 1 acre of park land per 1120 residents compared with 7.9 acres per 1000 residents for other large California communities (Fig. 1). As shown in Fig. 1, the darkest areas on the map surrounding the 92701 zip code represent the highest park poor area in Santa Ana with only 0.5 acres of land per 1000 residents (Trust for Public Land, 2005). They organized residents to identify a vacant lot central to the 92701 zip code. The identified parcels had three owners, the city, a community redevelopment agency and a private market. Advocacy efforts included: (1) prominent media engagement—an exposé feature article in La Opinión, a leading Spanish-speaking newspaper; (2) collecting and disseminating local surveillance data, where the overweight rate was 85% among children and youth living in a large condominium complex adjacent to the park construction site; and (3) leveraging resources—space for health promotion activities at the condominium complex home to an estimated 1000 residents. The market donated and transferred the ownership of their parcel to LHA at no cost. LHA negotiated a 40-year leasing agreement with the city 4 th St F a ir v ie w R d 1st St Chapm an Ave E l l i s A ve Ja m bo r e e R d 1st St B ri st o l S t M ain St T u st in S t B r i st o l S t M ichelson D r T h e C it y D r Gar den Gr ove Blvd H a rv ar d A ve La V eta Ave G ra n d A v e F a ir v ie w S t M a i n S t 1st St F a ir v ie w S t Talber t Ave San t a An a Blv d Bar r anca Pky M acar thur Blvd T u st in A v e H a rb o r B lv d 17th St G r a n d A v e Alton Pky Adam s Ave G ra n d A v e H a rb o r B lv d M acar thur Blvd F a ir v ie w S t 1st St Euclid S t E u cl id S t T o w n A nd Cou ntr y Rd D yer R d G la ss e l l S t R ed H i l l Ave W ar ner Ave M em or y Ln Chapm an Ave Baker St Edinger A ve 5th St H a rb o r B lv d M ac ar th u r B lv d W estm i n ster Ave B ri st o l S t W ar n er Ave W ar n er Ave Edi n ger Ave 17th St M a in S t P a rk e r S t 55 22 55 55 57 73 5 405 Colonel W.C. Eldridge Park Friendship Park Jerome Mabury Park Birch Park Logan ParkFrench Park Angels Park Sasser Park Prentice Park Windsor Park Edna park Centennial Regional Santa Ana Memorial Madison Park Delhi Park Adams Park Campesino Park Spurgeon Park El Salvador Park Lowell Park Heritage Park Santa Anita Park Bomo Koral Park Sandpointe Park Carl Thorton Park Lillie King Park River View Park Griset Park Santiago Park Sarah May Downie Fisher Park Portola Park Cabrillo Park Rosita Park Morrison Park Park Deficit Analysis Special thanks to the following data providers: Thomas Brothers, ESRI, and the CA Department of Education Map created by The Trust for Public Land on October 3, 2006 Created in ESRI ArcMap 9.1® Map Projection: NAD 1983 State Plane California VI FIPS 0406 Feet TPL, Trust for Public Land, and The Trust for Public Land logo are trademarks of The Trust for Public Land. Copyright © 2006 The Trust for Public Land. www.tpl.org Information on this map is provided for purposes of discussion and visualization only. Legend Number of Park Acres per 1,000 Kids 0.195 - 1.000 1.001 - 3.000 3.001 - 5.000 5.001 - 7.000 7.001 - 9.121 City of Santa Ana Parks and Open Space Waterbodies Transportation Interstate Highway Major Road Local Road Railroads This map shows the results of The Trust for Public Land’s Park Deficit Model. The park deficit model calculates how many acres of park or open space exist per 1,000 children under the age of 18 within city council districts. It then identifies those districts where there is an insufficient amount of parkland. Santa Ana, California 0 0.5 10.25 Mile Fig. 1. Park deficit analysis. 332 R. García et al. / Preventive Medicine 49 (2009) 330–333 333R. García et al. / Preventive Medicine 49 (2009) 330–333 for the remaining parcels at a cost of $2 per year, for a combined open space of 0.5 acres. In conjunction with a local hospital, LHA secured the pro bono services of two Southern California-based firms to build a safe, environmentally conscious and LEED-certified community center and park. The park will feature a basketball half-court, toddler playground, adolescent jungle gym, and walking path. Security features include wrought iron gates surrounding the park area, safety night lighting, and rest points for elderly users. These features and amenities were included to increase physical activity opportunities for children and their families, and promote community mobilization for a healthy community. Discussion These case studies illustrate how advocacy efforts have resulted in increased access to public resources related to physical activity in several Southern California communities. Given the current inequities in access to public resources in poor and ethnic minority commu- nities, continued advocacy efforts are vital. With regard to the development and use of public lands, we have proposed ten principles to guide policy makers, which we summarize here (See full text of principles in García and White, 2006). The process of decision-making regarding investment of public monies in the built environment need to be transparent and fair and guided by a comprehensive vision for promoting the health of the entire community. Policy-makers should prioritize projects that can meet multiple community needs as well as promote community health such as establishing public parks within the campuses of new and remodeled schools that can provide safe-space for physical activity and potentially remove pollutants from the water and mitigate runoff. Resources should first be allocated to low-income and ethnic minority communities in order to overcome the legacy of inequities in access to high quality public parks and schools. Standards for measuring equity must be established for agencies in order to track progress in building healthy and livable communities for all. Increased attention should be paid to ensuring that recipients of public funds comply with federal and state laws designed to achieve equal access to all public resources including Title VI of the Civil Rights Act of 1964 (i.e., prohibits discrimination on basis of race, color, or national origin for programs and activities conducted with federal funding) and parallel state laws. Finally, the community needs to be engaged and empowered to take part in all aspects of infrastructure decision-making and prepared to engage in advocacy efforts if the outcome of the decision-making process is not satisfactory. Given the agenda of the new federal administration and availability of stimulus funds, many transportation infrastructure projects are underway. These projects must focus attention on ensuring that the low-income and ethnic minority communities benefit at least equally, and efforts should be made to redress past inequities. The subgroups most likely to benefit from increased access are low-income men and women living in resource-poor commu- nities. They have likely devoted their scarce resources to car ownership given the significant obstacles faced in accessing reliable public transport. Individuals in these same communities likely have little leisure time to spend in physical activity and reduced access to recreational facilities, parks or walking trails. Existing educational laws (i.e., “No Child Left Behind” and similar state laws) developed to primarily improve standard academic metrics should be amended to mandate the inclusion of physical education in federal monitoring and accountability. These efforts are likely to have the most benefit for low-income and ethnic minority populations for whom the childhood obesity epidemic is most severe and opportunities for physical activity outside of school are limited. Integration of physical activity into the school day is a prime example of a “push” strategy designed to make the healthy choice easier and unhealthy choice (i.e., remaining inactive) more difficult. Such strategies rely less on individual motivation and choice and thus may be more successful in engaging populations who typically do not participate in physical activity and who may be more likely to benefit (Yancey et al., 2007). Realization of the severity of the obesity and chronic disease epidemics and failure of individually focused interventions has led to heightened interest in implementing environmental interventions to increase physical activity. Although promising, the impact of these strategies in ultimately reducing the obesity epidemic will be limited by the presence of continued inequities in the distribution of physical activity-related resources in the community. Advocacy efforts are critically needed to ensure that all communities benefit equally from infrastructure projects designed to build healthy communities, effective public schools and safe and reliable transportation. Without continued advocacy efforts, the environmental strategies being implemented to increase physical activity levels in the population will lead to a widening versus narrowing of the gap between the health status of the wealthy and poor in this country. Conflict of interest statement The authors declare that there are no conflicts of interest. Acknowledgments The preparation of this paper was funded in part through a grant from the Centers for Disease Control and Prevention (CDC) and the National Cancer Institute (NCI) cooperative agreement for the Cancer Prevention and Control Research Networks (CPCRN) 1-U48- DP000056. References Babey, S., Hastert, T., Yu, H., Brown, E.R., 2008. Physical activity among adolescents when do parks matter? Am. J. Prev. Med. 34 (4), 345–348. Brown, E.R., Babey, S.H., Hastert, T.A., Diamant, A.L., 2005. Half of California adults walk less than one hour each week. Health Policy Res. Brief (PB2005-9), 1–8. California Center for Public Health Advocacy, 2006. Dropping the ball: California schools fail to meet physical education mandates. Available at http://www. publichealthadvocacy.org/droppingtheball.html. Accessed November 1 2008. Cawley, J., Meyerhoefer, C., Newhouse, D., 2007. The impact of state physical education requirements on youth physical activity and overweight. Health Econ. 16, 1287–1301. Dannenberg, A.L., Bhatia, R., Cole, B.L., Heaton, S.K., Feldman, J.D., Rutt, C.D., 2008. Use of health impact assessment in the U.S.: 27 case studies, 1999–2007. Am. J. Prev. Med. 34 (3), 241–256. Estabrooks, P.A., Lee, R.E., Gyurcsik, N.C., 2003. Resources for physical activity participation: does availability and accessibility differ by neighborhood socio- economic status? Ann. Behav. Med. 25 (2), 100–104. García, R., Fenwick, C., 2009. Social Science, equal justice, and public health policy: lessons from Los Angeles. J. Public Health Policy 30, S26–S32. García, R., Rubin, T., 2004. Cross Road Blues: transportation justice and the MTA consent decree. In: Lucas, K. (Ed.), Running on Empty, pp. 221–256. García, R., White, A., 2006. Healthy parks, schools, and communities: mapping green access and equity for the Los Angeles Region. The City Project Policy Report 8–9. Available at www.cityprojectca.org/ourwork/mappinggreenaccess/documents/ Healthy_Parks_Schools_Communities_textonly.pdf, accessed 31 October 2008. Lachapelle, U., Frank, L., 2009. Transit and health: mode of transport, employer- sponsored public transit pass programs, and physical activity. J. Public Health Policy 30 (SI), S73–S94. Mather, M. 2009. Most U.S. workers still driving alone. Population Reference Bureau. Accessed at http://www.prb.org/Articles/2008/commuting.aspx?p=1. Sacks, G., Swinburn, B., Lawrence, M., 2009. Obesity policy action framework and analysis grids for a comprehensive policy approach to reducing obesity. Obes. Rev. 10, 76–86. Tajik, M., Minkler, M., 2007. Environmental justice research and action: a case study in political economy and community-academic collaboration. Int. Q. Community Health Educ. 26 (3), 213–231. Trust for Public Land, 2005. City of Santa Ana Feasibility Study. Yancey, A.K., Fielding, J.E., Flores, G.R., Sallis, J.F., McCarthy, W.J., Breslow, L., 2007. Creating a robust public health infrastructure for physical activity promotion. Am. J. Prev. Med. 32, 68–78. work_a5o2l7z7b5dxnb76korflw7iju ---- Poetic Justice: Corruption in Lambton County, Canada West, 1854-1858 Copyright © The Ontario Historical Society, 2013 Ce document est protégé par la loi sur le droit d’auteur. L’utilisation des services d’Érudit (y compris la reproduction) est assujettie à sa politique d’utilisation que vous pouvez consulter en ligne. https://apropos.erudit.org/fr/usagers/politique-dutilisation/ Cet article est diffusé et préservé par Érudit. Érudit est un consortium interuniversitaire sans but lucratif composé de l’Université de Montréal, l’Université Laval et l’Université du Québec à Montréal. Il a pour mission la promotion et la valorisation de la recherche. https://www.erudit.org/fr/ Document généré le 5 avr. 2021 22:20 Ontario History Poetic Justice Corruption in Lambton County, Canada West, 1854-1858 Gregory Stott Volume 105, numéro 2, fall 2013 URI : https://id.erudit.org/iderudit/1050732ar DOI : https://doi.org/10.7202/1050732ar Aller au sommaire du numéro Éditeur(s) The Ontario Historical Society ISSN 0030-2953 (imprimé) 2371-4654 (numérique) Découvrir la revue Citer cet article Stott, G. (2013). Poetic Justice: Corruption in Lambton County, Canada West, 1854-1858. Ontario History, 105(2), 160–182. https://doi.org/10.7202/1050732ar Résumé de l'article A partir de 1855, Robert McBride (1811-1895), commerçant et receveur des postes dans le comté de Lambton, poète, Orangiste, et conservateur modéré, s’est considéré comme victime d’une conspiration organisée par des politiciens réformateurs intrigants et leurs amis. Dans ses livres de poésie, particulièrement ses Poems Sentimental & Satirical On Many Subjects Connected with Canada, se basant sur son expérience personnelle, il a décrit les agissements coupables des juges, de la classe des spéculateurs terriens, et autres personnes liées au mouvement réformiste du Haut-Canada, qui, d’après lui, sapaient et corrompaient les bases britanniques de la province. Les poèmes de McBride, et autres documents concernant ses difficultés légales, nous aident à comprendre les liens compliqués qui existaient parmi les administrateurs coloniaux au niveau local dans le Haut-Canada des années 1850. https://apropos.erudit.org/fr/usagers/politique-dutilisation/ https://www.erudit.org/fr/ https://www.erudit.org/fr/ https://www.erudit.org/fr/revues/onhistory/ https://id.erudit.org/iderudit/1050732ar https://doi.org/10.7202/1050732ar https://www.erudit.org/fr/revues/onhistory/2013-v105-n2-onhistory03917/ https://www.erudit.org/fr/revues/onhistory/ �60 ONTARIO HISTORY On 2 January 1856 the Court of General Quarterly Sessions and the Lambton County Court met at the Sarnia courthouse before his Honour Judge Charles Robinson, as- sisted by W.E. Wright, Alfred Fisher, and Froome Talfourd. The fifth case brought before the County Court was an action of Tort against Port Franks’ merchant and postmaster Robert McBride by Wid- der merchant Robert Rae.2 While the case of “Rae verses Mc- Bride” received a modicum of coverage in the local press, like many other simi- lar cases, it quickly faded from the public consciousness. It did not, however, fade from the memory of the defendant who remained convinced that he was a victim not only of a miscarriage of justice, but also of a deliberate conspiracy. However dubious the claims may seem to subse- quent investigators, McBride believed that his downfall had been orchestrated by various representatives of the colo- nial government and administration in the Province of Canada. For McBride these apparent transgressions were ex- tremely personal, and yet, he felt, they were symptomatic of a pervasive cancer that was undermining Upper Canadian society. McBride also believed that these outrages were subverting the founda- tion of British values upon which he felt the colony and its society had been built. This was leading to the colony’s degradation and was forcing many of its “best sons” to find greener pastures in the United States. The Act of Union of 1841 had been foisted upon an unhappy and unwilling colonial population still grap- pling and reeling from the effects of two separate rebellions against the established Poetic Justice Corruption in Lambton County, Cana da West, 1854-18581 by Gregory Stott Ontario History / Volume CV, No. 2 / Autumn 2013 1 A much earlier version of this paper was presented in the History Department Seminar Series at Nipissing University on 8 October 2008. Special thanks to members of Nipissing’s Department of His- tory for their help and input and also to Michelle Vosburgh of Brock University, Sandra Barber of Univer- sity College of the North, Beth McAuley of Toronto, and the paper’s anonymous reviewers. 2 Sarnia Observer, 10 January 1856. Charles Robinson was born in Ireland in about 1817. Local ‘In- dian Agent’ Froome Talfourd was a native of England, born in 1809, while Sarnia’s postmaster Alfred Fish- er was born in England in about 1820. Canada Census, 1861, Sarnia Town. For a detailed examination of Upper Canada’s legal system in the first half of the nineteenth century see David Murray. Colonial Justice: Justice, Morality, and Crime in the Niagara District, 1791-1849 (Toronto: University of Toronto, 2002). inside pages autumn 2013.indd 160 2018-03-03 10:38:10 PM �6�corruption in lambton county, �854-58 authorities. While the rebellions had gained little support, at least in Upper Canada, the Union of the Canadas, which linked the predominantly Francophone- Catholic Lower Canada with the more generally Anglophone- Protestant Upper Canada, had just as little in the way of sup- port. It was a difficult union that stumbled along through sectar- ian, representational, economic, and political squabbles. The troubles facing this union would ultimately have much to do in initiating discussions that result- ed in Confederation in 1867.3 The colony’s internal dif- ficulties and problems aside, commentators at the time and many historians since have fre- quently lauded the fact that by the end of the 1840s the Union of the Canadas had managed to achieve entrenched responsible government, which in practice and spirit matched the full po- tential and rights of the colo- nists under what was ostensibly a British constitution and for the most part laid aside the di- visive issues of race and religion to create a particularly Canadian democracy. It seemed to put behind the colonies the old corruptions and abus- es of the apparently notorious “Fam- ily Compact” of the pre-rebellion period when cronyism had a stranglehold on pa- tronage and power.4However, McBride Abstract Beginning in 1855 Lambton County merchant, post- master, poet, Orangeman and moderate conservative Robert McBride (1811-1895) saw himself as a victim of a conspiracy launched by scheming Reform-minded politicians and their cronies. In books of poetry, particu- larly his hefty Poems Sentimental & Satirical On Many Subjects Connected with Canada, and drawing on his own experiences, he outlined the malfeasance of the ju- diciary, the ‘land jobbing’ class, and others associated with the Reform movement in Canada West who, he claimed, were undermining and corrupting the British foundations of the province. McBride’s poetry and other contemporary documentation about his legal travails help us understand the complex connections that existed among colonial administrators at the local level in Can- ada West in the 1850s. Résumé: A partir de 1855, Robert McBride (1811- 1895), commerçant et receveur des postes dans le comté de Lambton, poète, Orangiste, et conservateur modéré, s’est considéré comme victime d’une conspiration organ- isée par des politiciens réformateurs intrigants et leurs amis. Dans ses livres de poésie, particulièrement ses Po- ems Sentimental & Satirical On Many Subjects Con- nected with Canada, se basant sur son expérience person- nelle, il a décrit les agissements coupables des juges, de la classe des spéculateurs terriens, et autres personnes liées au mouvement réformiste du Haut-Canada, qui, d’après lui, sapaient et corrompaient les bases britanniques de la province. Les poèmes de McBride, et autres documents concernant ses difficultés légales, nous aident à compren- dre les liens compliqués qui existaient parmi les adminis- trateurs coloniaux au niveau local dans le Haut-Canada des années 1850. 3 J.M.S. Careless. The Union of the Canadas: The Growth of Canadian Institutions 1841-1857 (To- ronto: McClelland and Stewart, 1967), 222-23. S.J.R. Noel. Patrons, Clients, Brokers: Ontario Society and Politics, 1791-1896 (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1990), 130-33. 4 John Edwin Hodgetts. Pioneer Public Service: An Administrative History of the United Canadas, inside pages autumn 2013.indd 161 2018-03-03 10:38:11 PM �62 ONTARIO HISTORY felt differently. In fact he believed that if anything the situation had grown worse under the new order and he felt that his own experiences and observations proved this point. Far from promoting the inter- ests of the colonists, the Union, in his opionion, had seriously jeopardized the rights and values of what he saw as the core British nature of the predominantly Prot- estant Upper Canada or Canada West and threat- ened the underpinnings of its society. In the preface to his hefty volume of po- etry, Poems Sentimental & Satirical On Many Subjects Connected with Canada, in which he recounted his troubles and outlined the problems facing Canada West, McBride noted that the haemorrhaging of peo- ple had two causes “It is the land jobbing craft and the land jobbing craft; these are the principal actors. I have watched them for over thirty years. Previous to the union with the French, they were harmless; since then, they have got power they never had before, and have grown into monster leeches. These have pro- duced a boil, into which, if a probe was sent to the bottom, the pus that would 1841-1867 (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1955), 20, 46-47, 162-63; Noel, Patrons, Clients, and Brokers, 155-56. Certainly there was much anxiety over the control that the Reformers had over patronage under Robert Baldwin and Louis LaFontaine and the manner in which it was dispensed caused anger both within the ranks of the Reform movement as well as within the ranks of the more conservative opposition. John Clarke. Land, Power, and Economics on the Frontier of Upper Canada (Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2001), 449-55; John Ralston Saul. Extraordinary Canadians: Louis-Hippolyte LaFon- taine & Robert Baldwin (Toronto: Penguin, 2010), 5-6. Robert McBride’s Poems Satirical and Sentimenal, published in 1869, was his way of striking out at his many adversaries. inside pages autumn 2013.indd 162 2018-03-03 10:38:11 PM �63 come forth would astonish the people.”5 In a society where so much of the politi- cal culture was built on what S.J.R. Noel outlined as “clientalism” which he iden- tified as highlighting the important pat- tern of the useful connections between patrons and clients, there was much emphasis placed upon deference to so- cial and political betters.6 However, Mc- Bride was not alone complaining about the persistence of corruption within the Canadas which played a major role in unseating the administration of Francis Hincks in 1854.7 Corruption in the land distribution process was the core of McBride’s medi- cal metaphors. It was issues over land that had led to the emergence of a new and powerful “land jobbing” class that victim- ized all who crossed it. McBride had ob- served these people at work when he lived along the Grand River and found it again upon his arrival in Lambton County. In his great tomes of poetry, McBride—arch Tory and Orangeman—linked together the Canada Land Company, the judici- ary, and, overarching them all, the great Reform-minded politicians and their supporters. It was this last group who, through compromising their principles with the French-Catholic “other” and advancing their own policies and cronies, had, despite their claims, victimized Up- per Canadians and stunted the growth of the colony. As McBride further claimed, “If there was a good doctor that would begin and purify the blood first, he might then make a cure.”8 Poetry as a form of political activism was not unique to McBride, as American poets like Walt Whitman and William Davis Gallagher used poetry as a means of voicing political ideals and concerns. Even in Canada poems had been used 5 Robert McBride, “To the Reader,”Poems Sentimental & Satirical On Many Subjects Connected with Canada, Including A Complete Exposure of Our County Court, and Division Court System, in Several Theat- rical Acts & Dialogues, Showing How the People Have Been, and Are Now Victimized. All Tending to Prove on the Part of those Indicated, a Complete Conspiracy set up by them for the Purpose of Enslaving the people of this Country. Also a Dissertation on the Doings of the Canada Company’s Land, Jobbing, and other Matters (London, Ontario: Dawson Brothers, 1869), 3. On the issue of land and government land policies during the nineteenth century, see Michelle Vosburgh, “The Crown Lands Department: The Government and the Settlers of McNab Township, Canada West,” Ontario History 100:1 (Spring 2008); 80-100; Michelle Vosburgh, “Bending the Rules: Inspectors and Surveyors and Upper Canada’s Land Policies,” Ontario History 94:2 (November 2002); 148-64. Evidence of what McBride most decried about speculators and ‘land jobbing’ is amply described in David Shanahan, “Tory Bureaucrat as Victim: The Removal of Samuel Jarvis, 1842-47,” in Ontario History 95:1 (Spring 2003): 38-64. Kenneth C. Dewar’s study of Charles Clarke examines a prolific writer who would have been a political opponent of McBride. The study, how- ever, has much to say about a mid-nineteenth-century Canadian political writing. Kenneth C. Dewar. Charles Clarke: Pen and Ink Warrior (Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2002); xiii-xv, 47-70, 270-73. 6 S.J.R. Noel, 14-17. 7 Globe, 22 March 1855; Ibid., 14 May 1855; A Doubly Disappointed Settler, “More Land Jobbing!,” Globe, 6 July 1857; “Opinions of the Press: The Next Election,” copied from the Haldimand Independent in Globe, 10 November 1857. 8 McBride, “To the Reader,”Poems Sentimental & Satirical, 3; David Shanahan, “Tory Bureaucrat”, 45-47. corruption in lambton county, �854-58 inside pages autumn 2013.indd 163 2018-03-03 10:38:11 PM �64 ONTARIO HISTORY by French-Canadian nationalists in the lead up to the Rebellion of 1837-38.9 With their essential focus on his experi- ences, McBride’s poems provide a unique insight into aspects of the judicial sys- tem and the way land issues and courts were experienced by one individual. The poems penned by McBride are certainly not impartial and are far from accurate transcripts of the proceedings—which, if they existed, have not survived. They are largely based upon the memory of the writer, but, while he uses the alter ego “John Merchant,” the dates and pro- cedures to which he refers are consistent with those found in other more official records of the proceedings against him. McBride took much poetic license and imagined many of the exchanges based upon his own suppositions and possible paranoia. McBride’s writings cannot re- construct the actual trial transcripts, or properly evaluate his claims of injustice, but they do provide a fascinating and im- portant glimpse into perceived wrongs and the motivations for his political ac- tivism. Whatever fame or notoriety Robert McBride gained during his lifetime, it was probably quite local in its scope and extent. For the most part he appears to have laboured in relative obscurity, and while his work may have gained the at- tention of some in the 1860s and 1870s, it was almost certainly forgotten until pe- riodically dredged up by local antiquar- ians and journalists and occasionally his- torians. His published works, amounting to one hefty and two considerably lighter volumes of poetry, probably had a lim- ited shelf-life.10 A native of Ardstraw in the parish of Urblereagh in County Tyrone, Ireland, McBride was a product of his time and place. Born in late 1811 or early 1812 the self-styled “Canadian Orange Minstrel” had been well educated, later demon- strating his breadth of knowledge of Irish and British history, a competent grasp of the English language, and a devotion to the ideals of the British constitution.11 It is clear that, like many of his contem- poraries, McBride did not view Canada as much other than an extension of his native British Isles.12 The influence of his Orangeism had a huge role to play in 9 Jason Frank, “Aesthetic Democracy: Walt Whitman and the Poetry of the People,” Review of Poli- tics 69:3 (2007), 402-430; Terry A. Barnhart, “The Partisan: William Davis Gallagher and the Cause of Western Literature,” Ohio History 115 (2008), 101-120; Muriel Farley Dominguez, “Politics and Poetics: A Study of Nineteenth-Century Nationalist Verse in French Canada,” Nineteenth Century French Studies 21:1-2, (1992-1993), 168-79. 10 Arthur Ford, “Over the Weekend,” Sarnia Observer, 23 December 1946; Greg Stott. “Yon Sand- Beaten Shore”: The Story of Port Franks, Ontario (Arkona, Ontario: G. Stott Publishing, 1998), 11-23; Greg Stott, “‘The Chicago of the Dominion’?: The Development of Port Franks, Ontario.” Ontario His- tory 45 (Spring 2003), 22-37; Christina Burr, “‘Oil Mania’: Colonial Land Policy, Land Speculation, and Settlement in Enniskillen Township, 1830s-1860s,” Histoire sociale/ Social History 38:76 (2005), 305. 11 McBride, “Dreams and Reminiscences: Written March 1858,” Poems Sentimental & Satirical, 239, 242-43. 12.McBride, “Epistle to Mr. Davis,” and “Epistle From Davis,” Poems Satirical & Sentimental, 11-19. Catherine L. Albanese, “On the Matter of Spirit: Andrew Jackson Davis and the Marriage of God and Na- inside pages autumn 2013.indd 164 2018-03-03 10:38:11 PM �65corruption in lambton county, �854-58 his decision making. While the diversity of the Orange Order’s membership in British North America little resembled the greater homogeneity of the organi- zation in the British Isles, and seemed to be largely removed from the original conflicts in Ireland, the presence of a huge Francophone-Catholic popula- tion and the increasing influx of dispos- sessed Irish Catholic immigrants in the 1840s in the colonies gave the Order a particular resonance for many Protestant Canadians. Indeed, it was the antipathy toward Catholicism that provided even greater unity than the issue of loyalty to the Crown. McBride’s many references to the triumph of the Protestant religion in the struggles in Ireland and his espousal of the Protestant cause in Canada were clearly illustrated in his many poems celebrating the Order. He equated Ro- man Catholicism with backwardness and viewed adherents to the Roman Catholic Church—whether by design or ture,” Journal of the American Academy of Religion 60 (Spring 1992); 1-17. David Gagan, “George Taylor Denison,” Dictionary of Canadian Biography, vol. 10 (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1972), 224- 25; David Gagan. The Denison Family of Toronto 1792-1925 (Toronto: University of Toronto, 1973), 32- 43; David Mills. The Idea of Loyalty in Upper Canada, 1784-1850 (Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 1988), 58-59; J.M. Bumsted, “The Consolidation of British North America, 1783-1860,” Canada and the British Empire, ed. Philip Buckner (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008), 43. inside pages autumn 2013.indd 165 2018-03-03 10:38:11 PM �66 ONTARIO HISTORY default—as enemies of British freedoms and the well-being of Canada.13 Following his father’s death, McBride “secured the position of Seal Master or inspector of linens, in the Strabane Lin- en Hall, which position he held for six years.” At that juncture he resigned and immigrated to Canada sometime in the 1830s. According to later documenta- tion, upon arriving in the Upper Canada he settled in Hamilton, “entering into the grocery business,” before moving on to Oneida Township in nearby Haldi- mand County.14 By the early 1840s he was married to a woman whose name is unknown. Two sons were born of the un- ion, James in1841, and William in 1844. It was shortly thereafter that McBride’s wife died.15 He then married an Upper Canadian woman named Mary who was twenty years his junior; their daughter Elizabeth, was born in 1850. However, his second wife and young daughter died sometime during the early 1850s. Of these tragedies McBride made no men- tion in his writings.16 Early in 1851 McBride bore witness to what he saw as an outrage against a group of “persecuted people who have been shamefully abused by our Canadian Government.” This group of settlers had been squatters along the Grand River on lands dubiously transferred from the con- trol of the Six Nations Confederacy. This situation arose during a period of inter- necine disputes and rivalries between con- flicting political and bureaucratic institu- tions that had pitted Reformers against traditional Tories and helped to ensure the downfall of Indian Agent Samuel P. Jarvis. Changes in administration and reinterpretations of laws and agreements under the aegis of the Reformers and Governor General Lord Elgin had led to the forcible dispossession of the squatters. Whatever the legalities, McBride’s sense of justice was badly shaken when these people, who had “been encouraged to settle on these lands by a former Govern- ment,” were dispossessed of their homes and evicted. Given their experiences, many of these settlers either dispersed to the United States or sought refuge in the western parts of Canada West on Canada Company lands.17 Given his background, education and proclivities, this incident inflamed McBride’s anger over the steady loss of Canadians to the United States.18 As an Orangeman, McBride also saw a clear conspiracy of Catholics attempting 13 Scott W. See. Riots in New Brunswick: Orange Nativism and Social Violence in the 1840s (Toronto: University of Toronto, 1993); 71-76; Mills, The Idea of Loyalty in Upper Canada, 1784-1850, 85-87. Rob- ert McBride, “Come to Our Standard; Or Unions is Strength to Our Protestant Cause,” The Canadian Orange Minstrel (London, C.W.: London Free Press, 1860); 3-4. 14 Petrolia Advertiser, 21 November 1895. 15 McBride, “Obituaries: Written by the Author after the Death and Burial of his Eldest Son, who died at Oil Springs June 13th, 1862, Aged 20 Years 6 Months and 23 Days,” Poems Sentimental & Satiri- cal, 273. 16 McBride, “Moral” Poems Sentimental & Satirical, 276. 17 McBride, “A Dissertation On the Doings of the Canada Company’s Land Jobbing and Other Mat- ters,” Poems Sentimental & Satirical, 281; F.J.Cheshire Information for the Public Account of the Proceedings inside pages autumn 2013.indd 166 2018-03-03 10:38:11 PM �67corruption in lambton county, �854-58 to undermine the “true” British charac- ter of Canadian society, and this appar- ently “sinister” influence was directly un- dermining land tenure and the rights of Protestant settlers.19 While McBride railed against the fate of his friends and neighbours, he was not himself directly caught up in the dis- possession. He was, however, interested in looking for greener pastures, although he was determined to remain on British soil. McBride felt that the security of the Oneida and Tuscarora Township squat- ters had been guaranteed by the more conservative-minded regime of Metcalfe and his chief advisor William Henry Draper. The about-face with regard to these “persecuted people” was made un- der the aegis of the reform-minded Lord Elgin and the co-premiers Robert Bald- win and Louis-Hippolyte Lafontaine. While the politics and sectarian conflicts of his youth would heavily influence his subsequent writings and philosophies, McBride found that many of these con- cerns melded well with the new political situations that he found in his adopted land. McBride and other Orangemen of Loyalist and British background found ready applications of their politics and beliefs in the colony. Through his own observations and experiences, McBride came to equate upheaval, dislocation and injustice with the zeal and corruption at the root of the Reform movement.20 Whether or not McBride was part of the “moderate Toryism” that emerged in Upper Canada during the polarizing de- bates of the 1820s and 1830s, he seems to have harboured little faith in many Reform-minded politicians. As David Mills argued, Upper Canadians had be- come less swayed by the ideolog y of loy- alty than with its more practical political realities. There had been considerable disquiet about the extremism employed by traditional Tory authorities on the is- sue of loyalty, which equated reformist attitudes with disloyalty, American re- publicanism, and social chaos.21 McBride and Doings of the Government Commissioners Against the Unfortunate Settlers Upon the Indian Lands in the Townships of Tuscarora and Oneida, in the Years of our Lord 1846 and 1847 (Hamilton: Gazette Of- fice, 1847), 3-11. The crux of the issue was the fact that the Six Nations Confederacy whose lands flanked the Grand River had given so-called Brant Leases or Indian Deeds of land to various settlers from outside of the Confederacy, namely, people of non-First Nations background. Colonial authorities increasingly viewed these transactions as illegal for they maintained that the Crown alone protected and administered the rights of Upper Canada’s First Nations peoples. See John S. Hagopian, “Joseph Brant vs. Peter Russell: A Re-examination of the Six Nations’ Land Transactions in the Grand River Valley,” Histoire Sociale/Social History 30:60 (1997), 300-333 and Shanahan, “Tory Bureaucrat as Victim: The Removal of Samuel Jarvis, 1842-47,” 38-64. From the perspective of the settlers the new administration seemed to renege upon earlier promises and set up a board of commissioners to investigate the situation [D. Fraser to John S. Pakington, 28 May 1852, in Return to an Address of the Honourable The House of Commons dated 16 August 1853, 3]. 18 McBride, “Imprisonment for Debt Illustrated,” The Canadian Orange Minstrel (1860), 5 19 Robert McBride, “ON THE MURDER OF JAMES CAMPBELL BY THE ONEIDA PAPISTS, JULY 12, 1851. TUNE – “OUR COUNTRY ’S SAVIOUR.” The Canadian Orange Minstrel (1860), 12-13. 20 See, Riots in New Brunswick: Orange Nativism and Social Violence in the 1840s, 75. 21 Mills, The Idea of Loyalty in Upper Canada, 1785-1850, 71. inside pages autumn 2013.indd 167 2018-03-03 10:38:11 PM �68 ONTARIO HISTORY himself felt antipathy toward prominent Catholic politicians and held the Act of Union as the cause of the steady migra- tion to the United States. In a note ac- companying his poem “The Canadian Serpent” he argued that “Previous to our union with the French, very few Canadi- ans left the country, since then there has been a combination so unjust as to cause them to leave in thousands.” It was, from McBride’s perspective, a deliberate policy of Lower Canadian politicians and their associates to ensure that their population remained the larger part of the union.22 McBride suggested that many af- fected by the land seizures along the Grand River had been encouraged by promotional literature from the Canada Company to take up lands in Bosanquet Township on Lake Huron in the south- ern reaches of the Huron Tract. Having corresponded with company officials in Toronto, McBride was provided with a prospectus for the creation of a new town at the mouth of the Ausable River to be called Port Franks. McBride and at least two other parties from his neigh- bourhood attempted to secure land in the region, only to discover that Canada Company officials in the district capital of Goderich professed to know nothing of the plan. A flurry of confused corre- spondence and hastily issued disclaimers were sent. However, the Canada Com- pany now had to face the ire of McBride and other potential settlers who threat- ened legal action for being misled and for redressing possible costs. Indeed, Mc- Bride had already disposed of his Oneida property. Facing legal unpleasantness, Company officials immediately retracted their previous disavowals and dispatched surveyors to lay out the town plot of Port Franks. On 17 November 1851, Mc- Bride secured deeds for five one-quarter acre lots, although he would not relocate to Port Franks until early in 1854.23 By the time of his arrival, a small settlement of a few dozen squatting fishermen and lumbermen had grown up around a tav- ern started by Levi Stephens.24 According to his later musings, Mc- Bride’s difficulties began almost at once. While he was busy erecting his new busi- 22 McBride, “The Canadian Serpent,” Poems Sentimental & Satirical, 229-233. McBride, “ON THE TRAP FOR UPPER CANADA, AS SEEN BY PROTESTANT GEORGE AND PAPIST McGEE, JOINING HANDS,” The Canadian Orange Minstrel (1860), 5-6. See David A. Wilson, Thomas D’Arcy McGee: Volume I: Passion, Reason, and Politics, 1825-1857 (Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press, 2008), 32-35. 23 McBride, “A Dissertation On the Doings of the Canada Land Company’s Land Jobbing and Other Matters,” Poems Satirical & Sentimental 281-286. Circumstantial evidence suggests that his wife and daughter died during this period. Tina Loo has argued that in the scattered and isolated gold rush settle- ments of mid-nineteenth-century British Columbia the law and legal structures were used as a means of es- tablishing economic and social order. They were employed to provide for the orderly construction of civil society, ensuring property rights and cementing potentially disparate elements of colonial society together. Tina Loo. Making Law, Order, and Authority in British Columbia, 1821-1871 (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1994), 71-72, 92; 24 Stott, “‘The Chicago of the Dominion’”, 22-26; Bosanquet Township Assessments 1852 and 1853, Lambton Room Archives, Lambton County Library Headquarters, Wyoming, Ontario. inside pages autumn 2013.indd 168 2018-03-03 10:38:11 PM �69corruption in lambton county, �854-58 ness and home at Port Franks and secur- ing a post office for the community, of which he was to be postmaster, he again ran into difficulties with the Canada Company. Writing “to the Company for several parties who wanted to buy build- ing lots,” he was frustrated to receive no response. He learned that when the township council had written to Com- pany officials for lists of sold lots for the purposes of taxation, they had been in- formed “that there was no town there, nor likely never [sic] would be.”25 All further attempts to seek clarification on the mat- ter failed.26 McBride was then advised by unnamed parties to take legal action for having been lured “into the wilderness, under false pretences of a town being where the existence of which was denied by themselves.”27 Although he pursued legal action he was apparently the victim of an unscrupulous or incompetent law- yer. McBride insinuated that his suit— and by inference any suit—against the Canada Company was useless “because money can bribe and do anything with too many of the lawyers we have at the present day.”28 Whether he was aware of it or not similar complaints surrounded other Canada Company lands in How- ick Township were “land jobbing” duped other settlers while other commentators exposed politicians having “engaged in land jobbing and other practices unwor- thy of statesmen”.29 McBride’s land prob- lems were still unresolved when he was overtaken by other legal woes.30 In 1854 McBride secured the po- sition of postmaster at Port Franks through the aegis of Postmaster Gen- eral Malcolm Cameron. As McBride poetically explained he was informed by Cameron’s cronies that as, “you are one [who] receives the bounty;/ So you will use, without objection,/ Your voice, and vote at our election.”31 However, given that McBride’s political proclivities were better aligned with Cameron’s oppo- nent, George Brown, and the fact that he objected to having his vote bought, he 25 McBride, “Dissertation,” Poems Satirical & Sentimental, 288. 26 Bosanquet Township Minutes, 6 March 1854, 27 November 1855, and 16 April 1856. 27 McBride, “Dissertation,” Poems Satirical & Sentimental, 289. 28 Ibid. 29 A Doubly Disappointed Settler, “More Land Jobbing!,” Globe, 6 July 1857; “Opinions of the Press: The Next Election,” copied from the Haldimand Independent in Globe, 10 November 1857. The situa- tion in Howick was not dissimilar to that faced by McBride at Port Franks. The settler was issued with a receipt by John Clarke, the Crown Land Agent at Goderich—the same man McBride had dealings with in 1851—but when he went to make his second payment he “was refused on the ground that the land had been sold to other parties!” A commission of inquiry established that there had been a mistake. However, it was later explained “that the second instalment cannot be taken from me or my friends, as the lots were sold to other parties in April, 1854, just four months prior to the Government public sale in Goderich, at which our purchase was made, and instalments paid.” The aggrieved settler demanded to know whether “our land granting department will be placed in a state of efficiency, and disappointed settlers cease to be driven to seek lands where they at least receive straightforward and honourable treatment—in the United States?” 30 Sarnia Observer, 26 April 1855. 31 McBride, “County Court,” Act 1, Scene 1, Poems Satirical & Sentimental, 19. inside pages autumn 2013.indd 169 2018-03-03 10:38:11 PM �70 ONTARIO HISTORY publically refused to cast his vote for his benefactor, whatever his perceived debt. In his essay “Dissertation” he chose a nar- rative voice to further explain that: About this time there had been an election in this County [Lambton], and one of the Bailiffs being anxious to secure the return of his man, and seeing and knowing that the writer had a good many bills due him over the country; this Bailiff wanted to get them out of his hands for collection, which would have been a good thing before an elec- tion, but the Bailiff was told that he was not in the habit of suing unless he could not help it, and would give no bills. This Bailiff then asked him for his vote for his friend, and threatened him if he would not vote as he wanted him (this is the whipping-in season), that he would suffer. The reason he said was, because his friend had great interest in the country. He then told the Bailiff that the very threat would cause him to vote for his opponent, if he even thought he was no better than the other. But just as sure as the Bailiff threatened, and immediately after the election the trouble began, but so long as an old gentleman, “who was then judge,” sat on the bench, they could do him little harm. This Judge was one of the old appointments, but he was soon exchanged for another.32 While Upper Canadian elections frequently included discord, threats and even violence, campaigns in Lambton and neighbouring Huron counties had been particularly contentious affairs, es- pecially in the early 1850s when a seri- ous split in the Reform camp emerged.33 32 McBride, “Dissertation,” Poems Satirical & Sentimental, 289-90. 33 John Garner. The Franchise and Politics in British North America, 1755-1867 (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1969), 198-99, 200-209. The Hon. Malcolm Campbell, the target of much of McBride’s wrath. Credit: Topley Studio, Library and Archives Canada. PA 025476. inside pages autumn 2013.indd 170 2018-03-03 10:38:12 PM �7�corruption in lambton county, �854-58 While McBride had been angered by the about-face shown in the Grand River land issue by the Reform ministry of Baldwin and Lafontaine, he, like many of the government’s detractors, must have been heartened by the fracturing of the old-Reform alliances. In part this fissure was sparked by Toronto’s George Brown who was fearful of the new ministry un- der Francis Hincks and Augstin-Norbert Morin, which was positioning itself as an administration of government and church in an attempt to cement support with Roman Catholic reformers in Low- er Canada. Having alienated Brown and his influential Globe, Hincks had turned to Malcolm Cameron, who, though an independent, had campaigned against Brown, Alexander Mackenzie, and the Central Reform Association of Lamb- ton. Cameron had pointed them out as anti-Catholic and as sowers of discord. Brown, in turn, had denounced Cam- eron as a “political-turncoat” and referred to him as a “Coon”—a name that would remain attached to Cameron and would find ready acceptance by McBride in his future wrangles and writings.34 McBride probably knew of Cameron before he arrived in Lambton County, given the latter’s prominence in provin- cial politics and the role he had played in toppling chief superintendent Jarvis. Whatever feelings he harboured toward Cameron, McBride acknowledged the fact that he owed his appointment as postmaster of Port Franks to Cameron who had been postmaster general until the fall of the Hincks’ ministry late in 1854.35 It was certainly no secret that, in order to secure voters, “Mr. Cameron and all the satellites of Government within reach are traversing the county day and night... [p]romises of office are freely made, new post offices are being erected at every corner.”36 Cameron’s use of public office for political or pecuni- ary gain was well known, and in 1853 he had secured the services of a well-known Conservative commentator to conduct a survey of the Ottawa River valley ostensi- bly for settlement purposes, but in an area 34 Margaret Coleman, “Malcolm Cameron,” Dictionary of Canadian Biography, vol 10 (Toronto: University of Toronto, 1972), 124-29; J.M.S. Careless. Brown of the Globe: Vol. One: The Voice of Upper Canada, 1818-1859 (Toronto: Macmillan Co. of Canada, 1959), 137-41; A.J. Johnston. Lambton County Names and Places: Revised Edition (Sarnia: Lambton County Council, 1942), 37. 35 McBride, Poems Satirical & Sentimental, 19. Cameron was Post Master General of the Canadas as late as 1 September 1854, a full month after McBride took up his post and opened the first post office at Port Franks. A year after he left that office, Cameron’s influence was still being felt when he requested that his successor, Robert Spence, fill a vacancy at the Dundas post office with a man he recommended. In reporting the matter to W.H. Griffin, Spence noted that while “Cameron asks me to appoint John to the letter carrier—I am so fond of C. that I would like to meet his wishes—as I do in most things he asks me—Cameron is a good judge of Character... the great misfortune with John is that he is entirely destitute of Education and not brain enough to remember two messages at one time.” Robert Spence, PMG, to W.H. Griffin, post office appointments, 4 August 1855. Post Office Department, Department Circular, Quebec 1 September 1854, “Reconstruction of the Inspector’s Office Districts, into the London, Toronto, Kingston, and Montreal Divisions”, Malcolm Cameron, Postmaster General. Library and Archives Cana- da, Post Office Fonds, RG 3, Vol. 1007, Folder 7, 1851-58. 36 Globe, 20 July 1854. inside pages autumn 2013.indd 171 2018-03-03 10:38:12 PM �72 ONTARIO HISTORY where Cameron’s associates had timber interests.37 Cameron’s shady dealings led to damaging accusations by his political opponents.38 Whether McBride was will- ing to admit to it, this appointment came with an expectation of future support. Cameron would expect that his patron- age would not go unrewarded. McBride’s failure, and indeed his vehement refusal to reciprocate along with his support for Cameron’s political opponent George Brown—whose anti-Catholic attitudes accorded more closely with McBride’s— in the 1854 contest would make things difficult.39 From McBride’s perspective, his troubles increased infinitely after he, in good faith, purchased a fishing boat from one Abraham Goister, a transaction that, while witnessed, curiously was not docu- mented with a receipt. According to the stylized testimony developed by Mc- Bride, the boat was sold “About the very first of May” in 1855.40 While little is known about Goister with any certainty, it is clear that by the summer of 1855 he was in serious financial difficulties and ultimately forced to sell most of his prop- erty and holdings at a bailiff ’s sale. As the Sarnia Observer—a paper patronized by Cameron—reported, the Scottish-born Widder merchant Robert Rae claimed to have purchased the same boat at the bailiff ’s sale.41 According to McBride, he was served with a “Summons and Ac- count” on 20 September 1855.42 As his alter ego, John Merchant, ranted in the poetic recounting of the events: “These rascals all, I knew them well!/ See how they work their magic spell; I bought that boat, and paid the cash,/ How dare they send me here such trash;/ I must be off and get subpoeneas [sic],/... With time and money I’ll secure them.”43 On 1 November 1855, the Lambton County Court issued a Summons of Trover—a suit alleging the wrongful or fraudulent alienation of property—against Robert McBride who duly appeared with his lawyer William Vidal.44 Robert Rae had already established himself, at least in McBride’s eyes, as a chief adversary both as a competing, and apparently indebted, businessman and a political hopeful in the nearby village of Widder.45 In 1856 Rae launched his 37 Globe, “Mr. Turner’s Appointment,” 12 March 1853. 38 Coleman, “Malcom Cameron,” 127. 39 S.J.R. Noel. Patrons, Clients, Brokers, 13-14, 179, 182-83; Shanahan, 47-49. 40 Sarnia Observer 10 January 1856; McBride, Poems Satirical & Sentimental, 35; Bosanquet Town- ship Minutes, 15 April 1856. 41 Sarnia Observer, 10 January 1856 and 3 July 1856. 42 McBride, Poems Satirical & Sentimental, 23. 43 Ibid. 44 Archives of Ontario, RG 22-2766-0-1, Lambton County, Count Court Appearance Book, 1853- 1860, 1878, 18. Robert Rae Plaintiff vs. Robert McBride. 45 Sarnia Observer, 3 July 1856. Rae appears to have at least hinted that McBride’s role in this matter may have been to simply prevent him from receiving the monies that were due to him, suggesting, as Mc- Bride himself would assert, personal or political antipathy. inside pages autumn 2013.indd 172 2018-03-03 10:38:12 PM �73corruption in lambton county, �854-58 political career by running for a seat on Bosanquet Township council. That same July he secured the appointment as Wid- der’s postmaster, a community that had become an important centre of trade and commerce.46 Unlike McBride, Rae’s sup- port for Cameron was unwavering. Upon being questioned by the judge about the veracity of the claim made against him, “John Merchant” responded emphati- cally, “No! He owes me a large amount./ I’ll show my books, and then you’ll see/ How his account and mine agree:/ I owe him not, nor never did/ Go in his debt— the fates forbid!”47 Rae’s counsel Joshua Adams—who would be immortalized by McBride as “Mr. Positive”—had been born near Perth where his father had been warden of the Bathurst District. The younger Adams had attended the District Gram- mar School before studying law and had practised in his native town from 1848 to 1851. He then sojourned for a few years in the lumber business before moving to Sarnia in 1855, where he resumed the law practice which included the manage- ment of none other than the Honour- able Malcolm Cameron’s businesses and interests.48 Thus, there was a double con- nection to Cameron that would be given great scrutiny by McBride, for he believed that Cameron was the chief architect of his difficulties and persecutions. Al- though he would vehemently condemn Cameron, McBride never implicitly or explicitly admitted any debt or gratitude he might owe for having been awarded the office of Port Franks’ postmaster. McBride was represented by one of Lambton County’s most well-connected lawyers, William Penrose Vidal. The son of a captain in the Royal Navy who had become Sarnia’s first collector of customs, Vidal had accompanied his family to Up- per Canada in 1834. His elder brother, Alexander, became a provincial land surveyor and in 1853 had been named an agent for the Bank of Upper Canada. Part of Sarnia’s elite, the Vidals remained prominently connected to the local Tory and later Conservative establishment.49 On 2 January 1856 the case of “Rae verses McBride” was the fifth of seven cases put before the justices. As the Sar- nia Observer reported: Action of Tort, brought to recover the value of a fishing boat, claimed by the Plaintiff, as having been purchased by him at a Bailiff ’s sale, as then being the property of a person of the name Goister; but which was claimed by the Defendant as having been purchased by him from said Goister, some time previously, the Bailiff ’s sale having been made on an execution against him as the reputed owner of the boat, at the instance of the plaintiff, but retained by the Deft., on the plea of a previous sale made by Goister to him.50 Writing of his experiences in the format 46 Commemorative Biographical Record of the County of Lambton, Ontario (Toronto: J.H. Beers, 1906); 36-38. 47 McBride, Poems Satirical & Sentimental, 24. 48 Commemorative Biographical Record of the County of Lambton, Ontario, 384-85. 49 Ibid., 1-2. 50 Sarnia Observer, 10 January 1856. inside pages autumn 2013.indd 173 2018-03-03 10:38:12 PM �74 ONTARIO HISTORY of a play, McBride remained unswerving in his assertions that “This boat, I bought her long ago,/ And worked her with my men, I’ll show,/ That I possession long had got,/ And paid her price down on the spot.” While in his published work he generally refrained from naming his accusers directly, he allowed himself at least one exception when he made note of the fact that Goister “who sold this boat away,/ Was put in Court by Rip and Rae [author’s emphasis]”.51 At least in hindsight, from McBride’s perspective, it seemed that everyone as- sembled in the courtroom was against him. Just as the case of “Rae verses Mc- Bride” was to be taken up, there was a call made for the court to adjourn for lunch. However, according to McBride’s account, as the members of the jury left the courtroom, he received intelligence that there was a deliberate “plan to get a packed jury.” When six of the twelve jurors failed to return after lunch, Mc- Bride, in poetic form, alleged that Judge Robinson (to whom McBride applied the pseudonym of Blunderbrains) sum- moned six replacements; one of whom was a cousin of the bailiff, another was “a willing imp,” another was a relation to one of Rae’s principal supporters, and a fourth was simply described as having “the thick lip.”52 Adams brought forward several witnesses who spoke on behalf of Rae and claimed that the sale of the boat had been a deliberate fraud. The bailiff was vehement that when he went to seize the boat from McBride’s wharf that the merchant had threatened his life and come after him with various weapons. These were claims that Adams played up and McBride vociferously denied. In response to all of these allegations and witnesses, however, McBride’s lawyer Vidal—to whom he later referred to as “Mr. Simple”—called upon Goister to take the stand. In McBride’s rendition, Goister was adamant that “I sold that boat I truly say,/ About the very first of May;/ Defendant paid me every cent,/ I sold the boat and don’t repent.” When Vidal asked Goister how the payment had been made Goister responded that McBride had “paid in goods and note of hand” and that there was a witness to this transaction and that the note had since been passed to another merchant. How- ever, when Adams commenced the cross- examination, he confronted Goister with the allegation that “I think I’ve heard some others tell/ That you had said you did not sell?” To this Goister (identified simply as “F. Owner” in McBride’s dra- matic rendering ) said, “I never told such words as that/ To John or Than, the lying brat;/ I was paid down, without a doubt,/ Thirty pounds, or thereabout.”53 Adams then called upon the alleged witness to 51 McBride, “John Merchant’s Vision of the Great Beast of Lambton,” Scene VIII, Poems Satirical & Sentimental, 30. 52 McBride, “County and Division Court Taxes,” Poems Satirical & Sentimental, 31-33. McBride’s charge of jury-rigging came during a decade when reform of the institution in Canada West had sought to do away with earlier excesses and corruption. R. Blake Brown, A Trying Question: The Jury in Nineteenth- Century Canada (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2009), 8-9, 133-44, 157-58. 53 McBride, Poems Satirical & Sentimental, 35-36. inside pages autumn 2013.indd 174 2018-03-03 10:38:12 PM �75corruption in lambton county, �854-58 the transaction, a man that McBride cryp- tically called ‘Harrow Fib’ whose stylized testimony explained, “That note I never saw nor drew,/ Nor was there such a note in view./ If such a note has ever been/ By me the like was never seen;/ I do deny all knowledge of it,/ And swearing false I do not covet./ The note was false if such there was,/ To cheat the plaintiff by the laws;/ For me I have no more to say,/ But that I’m clear from Rip and Rae,/ I was no partner with them there,/ Nor have I in this case a share.”54 Adams produced other rebuttal wit- nesses—“Captain Buck” and “Mr. De- ist”—who backed up Harrow Fib’s testi- mony.55 McBride’s later writings make it abundantly clear that he had little faith in his legal counsel. If McBride’s poetic ren- dering of the trial is to be believed, then it seems that Vidal gave up on a vigorous defence and resorted to making apolo- gies for his client. As McBride told it, in his dramatic retelling of events in his fi- nal summations to the jury, Vidal or “Mr. Simple” explained, “I’m sorry gents, that I must show/ How my poor client little know [sic],/ And sorry, too, that he has spoken/ Such reckless things as here be- token;/ That he’s a man of shallow wit,/ And cannot things in order put;/ Such cannot live up to the fashion,/ But this I hope will be a caution/ To every man who hears his case,/ I speak it here be- fore his face;/ I’m sorry for him, bear in mind,/ I hope you’ll use him very kind;/ He has done wrong without his knowl- edge,/ And like yourselves, ne’er got to college;/ I’m sorry for him, and distrest,/ My very heart sinks in my breast;/ What can I do but plead his case,/ You jurymen all know your place.”56 If the essence of the proceedings was accurately recounted by McBride, then the outcome was a foregone conclusion. Outside observers may have shared some of McBride’s scepticism about the proc- ess, for the more objective Sarnia Ob- server reported that “[t]he evidence was very contradictory, but the jury returned a verdict for the Plaintiff for £20.”57 McBride’s portrayal of the county judiciary was highly unflattering, not- ing that “they have their cloaks like to a raven/ Standing in courts your money cravin’;/ They’ll cock their nose, and wag their jaw,/ An point their fingers to the law.” He further cautioned, “If you’re a stranger, sir, beware,/ And of their trover acts take care.”58 In particular, McBride saved his most biting criticism for the well-connected Judge Charles Robinson who had been appointed to the bench on 30 September 1853.59 Despite being a rel- atively recent emigrant from Dublin, Ire- land, Robinson had quickly established 54 Ibid., 36. 55 Ibid., 37. 56 Ibid., 37-38. 57 Sarnia Observer, 10 January 1856. 58 McBride, “Dialogue Between The Client and the Lambton Ghost On Going From Court,”Poems Satirical & Sentimental, 41. 59 Appendix to the Fourteenth Volume of the Journals of the Legislative Assembly of the Province Canada . . . 15th February to the 1stt July 1856 19 Victoria Appendix (No. 64), 185. inside pages autumn 2013.indd 175 2018-03-03 10:38:12 PM �76 ONTARIO HISTORY his legal credentials and been appointed to the bench in Perth County before be- ing permitted to switch his posting with Judge Read Burrett of Sarnia. His rise to prominence was helped in no small part by his connections to Upper Cana- da’s chancellor, William Hume Blake, whose sons, Edward and Samuel, were apparently Robinson’s nephews.60 In his satirical recounting of his trial, McBride referred to Robinson or “Judge Blun- derbrains” in a scathing footnote “This family of Blunderbrains are very numer- ous. There are many of that name now presiding over our County and Division Courts, because we hear of them being in many parts of Canada, if reports are true. They have got many relatives also in ac- tive business whose names are Catchpoll and Cheatim, they are all connected, and are the great grand-children of one great father, whose name was Persecution, but who changed his name on coming to this country, many years ago.”61 Similarly, McBride charged that there was a con- certed effort upon the part of the offic- ers of the court to slander and defame his character, given that he was “a stranger”. It was a deft move, however, for McBride acknowledged that the tactic drew “the people’s attention away from seeing the wrong inflicted.”62 Unwilling to accept the verdict, Mc- Bride appealed his conviction by apply- ing for a new trial which was granted for 1 July 1856. McBride maintained “that he had a bona fide interest in the boat.” Both sides of the case appear to have spent more time and resources in preparing for their second showdown because of a total of eighteen witnesses were called to testify, eight for Rae and ten for McBride. As in the early trial, it was noted that “[t]he evidence adduced on the trial was exceedingly contradic- tory—making it very difficult to arrive at a satisfactory conclusion as to whom the boat ‘properly’ belonged.” As the Sarnia Observer assessed “[T]he turning point of the case seemed to be,—Was the sale of the boat made by Goister to McBride bona fide, and for good consideration, and not merely for the purpose of pre- venting the present plaintiff from receiv- ing the amount of his claim against Go- ister.”63 Unfortunately for McBride, the jury “appeared to be of the opinion that the sale was fraudulent in its nature.”64 While the second verdict was clearly a blow to McBride, he was not about to concede defeat. Indeed, he immediately began a campaign to prove that his oppo- nents had conspired against him and that many of the witnesses had perjured them- selves in court. McBride imagined what might have transpired once word of his intended challenge reached Robinson, Adams, and Vidal. He was confident that 60 Sarnia Observer, 20 February 1901; Donald Swainson, “William Hume Blake,” Dictionary of Ca- nadian Biography, vol. 9 (Toronto: University of Toronto, 1976), 55-59; J. Rordans, Upper Canada Law Directory for 1858 (Toronto: J. Rordans, 1858), 104. 61 McBride, “County and Division Court Taxes,” Satirical & Sentimental, 23. 62 Ibid., 26. 63 Sarnia Observer, 3 July 1856. 64 Ibid. inside pages autumn 2013.indd 176 2018-03-03 10:38:12 PM �77corruption in lambton county, �854-58 his collection of materials would cause a scandal and prove that perjury and cor- ruption had reigned against him in the court. Accordingly, at least his poems al- leged, there was then a concerted effort to give his “name a bad report” in the hopes that it would stop him from pro- ceeding further. McBride seems to have viewed his own erstwhile counsel to be the lesser of the three conspirators, mo- tivated more by a fear that his colleagues might be exposed for immoral and even illegal activity. McBride surmised that his counsel was troubled by his client’s apparent thirst for vengeance and felt merely that “Respected men should not be mark’d,/ In open Court with shame;/ When hidden malice, mean and dark,/ Is all that gives them blame.”65 Whether McBride had any evidence whatsoever or merely gave vent to his wild imaginings, he explained in metre how Robinson had approached Queen’s Counsel to explain that McBride was simply a troublemaker who was badger- ing the court and, having lost, was merely attempting to undermine the prestige of the judiciary. This, from McBride’s per- spective, explained why, upon presenting his case and evidence of perjury to the Queen’s Counsel, he was informed that he would need to wait until the last day of the assizes to present the matter be- fore a magistrate he called “Doctor An- gler,” which may have been a thinly veiled pseudonym for Alfred Fisher. Upon ap- pearing before the magistrate with eleven witnesses who were willing to swear on his behalf, McBride presented his case and related documents and explained that the legal nightmare in which had become embroiled had “bled my pockets till they’ll bleed no more.” To his horror, however, the magistrate, was unsympa- thetic and disputed McBride’s allega- tions of conspiracy and corruption as “All bosh!” McBride then suggested that his persecutors had managed to sway the magistrate who then violently lashed out at the complainant and his allegations and threatened to fine him for contempt and categorically refused to hear any more, either from McBride or from his witnesses.66 Having exhausted both his legal and fiscal options, McBride found himself nearly penniless. The bailiff descended upon his property seizing the goods in his store as well as his home to meet the demands of the verdict as well as all other legal costs. From McBride’s perspective, however, the forces that were against him conspired to inflict one final blow by concocting another bogus claim that would finish him off once and for all. Ap- parently at the urging of his enemies in Sarnia, a Division Court Clerk—whom McBride called “James Needy”—was dis- patched on a round trip of some thirty- four miles to secure from Robert Rae a sworn affidavit on 27 December 1856 which attested to McBride’s duplicity in asserting that he “hath parted with his property, or made some secret or fraudu- 65 McBride, “Dialogue II”, Poems Satirical & Sentimental, 52. 66 McBride, “Dialogue V”, Poems Satirical & Sentimental, 61. inside pages autumn 2013.indd 177 2018-03-03 10:38:12 PM �78 ONTARIO HISTORY lent conveyance thereof, in order to pre- vent its being taken in execution.”67 The court now assessed that McBride was ow- ing £41, 4, 9.68 Faced with these allega- tions, a mounting debt and with no more resources to fight them, McBride was per- suaded by his counsel, the same William Vidal or Mr. Simple, to concede defeat. McBride reluctantly reported to Sarnia on 17 January 1857 to be incarcerated in the debtor’s ward of the Lambton Coun- ty Jail. According to McBride, he was met by none other than Malcolm Cameron himself who personally conducted him into his new quarters and condescend- ingly recounted how “The Lord provides for those in need;/ To sit and take their ease.”69 Then in what must have been ut- terly the product of McBride’s imagina- tion, Cameron returned to debrief the co-conspirators and “thank you for un- wearied zeal,/ In working out my plan;/ We’ll fix him how, he’s fast in jail,/ This most insulting man.” Cameron then al- legedly pressured the jailor to do his best to break McBride’s spirit by feeding him substandard food. McBride, however, held out, refusing the paltry offerings un- til the third day. On that day he informed the jailor that “he never would eat what he brought him. After this he was used like a human being.”70 McBride was incarcerated, separated from his children, and left with few real options. However, his attorney, William Vidal, informed him that he could apply for relief under the Insolvent Debtors Act. By the provisions of this Act, Mc- Bride would have to surrender “up all his property into the hands of parties whom the law styled trustees.” Having done this he would then publish notices in the Canada Gazette and the local Sarnia Ob- server and write personally to his credi- tors advising him of this decision. Mc- Bride was reluctant to do so, but seeing little alternative, he followed the advice. On 18 January 1857 McBride made the necessary appeals and put forward his claims.71 Forced to give up his books, records, and “Bills Receivable,” McBride found himself once more at the mercy of the court. It was McBride’s contention that the monies owed to him, of which he claimed to have kept a careful record, amounted to “nearly double the amount of the unjust debt and law costs included.” However, although he had provided Vi- dal with money to pay for the notices in the Observer and the Gazette, the notice was printed in the latter only twice and not the required three times. Therefore, when McBride appeared before the court again to plead his case and be freed, be- cause the third notice had not been pub- lished, “the Judge would not proceed,” and McBride was again remanded until the case could be heard in another three weeks. The reason for this delay, McBride 67 McBride, Poems Satirical & Sentimental, 69. 68AO, RG 22-2766-0-1 Lambton County, County Court Appearance Book, 1853-1860, 1878, 18. 69 McBride, Poems Satirical & Sentimental, 71. 70 Ibid., 72; Sarnia Observer, 9 April 1857. 71 Sarnia Observer, 22 January 1857. inside pages autumn 2013.indd 178 2018-03-03 10:38:12 PM �79corruption in lambton county, �854-58 alleged, was that even then in the Legis- lative Assembly the Hon. John Hillyard Cameron (no relation to McBride’s nem- esis Malcolm Cameron) had introduced a bill to abolish the provisions that per- mitted debtors to go through the proc- ess and regain their freedom. The bill, McBride charged, was pushed “through with all the power with which [Mal- colm Cameron’s]... brethren of the long robe were able to help him.”72 Echoing McBride’s own claims one of the bill’s chief critics was Lambton’s representa- tive George Brown who charged “that a certain number of persons had been al- lowed to get the full benefit of this Act. Others had taken the same pains but the judges had heard some cases and post- poned others, perhaps for some personal reason.”73 Passed as it was on 31 March 1857 and taking immediate and retro- active effect, the Act quashed McBride’s hope for rapid release. However, the new legislation did allow that any debtor who had attempted to gain freedom under the provisions of the old bill would be per- mitted to have his books and properties returned to him from the trustees. Mc- Bride reported that despite this right and his own attempts to see it done the judge never acted and McBride never received his records back. As a result, he had no records of the monies owed to him and no legal means of seeing that they were collected. There only remained the debt and costs over which he had been con- victed.74 As McBride explained, as a result of the new Act, there were some 600 debtors incarcerated in the prisons of Upper Canada with no legal recourse to gain their freedom, other than by pay- ing their original debt. He argued that fear of this “lawfully acknowledged rob- bery” resulted in thousands fleeing to the United States with negative results, “This injured the creditors more than anything else, because the property left behind them was eaten up by lawyers, sheriffs, and bailiffs. But then these unfortunate debtors did right when the laws of their own country would not protect them. If they could have stopped at home, they would have saved their creditors a great deal, but putting their property into the best shape to pay them.”75 In this allegation McBride saw the Canada Company in full complicity, by encouraging immigration yet holding debts and failure to pay as a threat over the poor settlers of the Huron District who, to save themselves from incarcera- tion, were “forc’d to fly from Huron.”76 72 McBride, Poems Satirical & Sentimental, 85-87. 73 “Insolvent Debtors Act,” Globe, 7 March 1857. 74 Appendix to the Fifteenth Volume of the Journals of the Legislative Assembly of the Province of Canada 20 Victoria Appendix 44, 1857, No. 11. Charles Robinson submitted the names of Robert McBride and David Buchanan of Sarnia. Interestingly enough while Buchanan’s debt was listed at £3,675 it was further noted that his “Assets assumed at £2,925.” However, while McBride’s debt was listed at £218 there was no listing of his assets. Sarnia Observer, 26 March 1857. Donald Swainson, “John Hillyard Cameron,” Dic- tionary of Canadian Biography, vol. 10 (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1972), 118-24. 75 McBride, “Huron Frog Pond,” Poems Satirical & Sentimental, 88. 76 McBride, “Canada Company’s Walking Beam,” Poems Satirical & Sentimental, 92. inside pages autumn 2013.indd 179 2018-03-03 10:38:12 PM �80 ONTARIO HISTORY In this way he tied the issue of “land jobbing” in the Canada Company lands with those of land speculators and land policies that had displaced the settlers in Haldimand. It was, from McBride’s per- spective, an officially sponsored outrage that was controlled by a small but pow- erful elite that dominated in the areas of politics, land speculation, and the judici- ary, something other critics also seemed to assert.77 McBride would languish in prison until March 1858. At this point he was something of a broken man who had no other recourse than to sign a certificate of surrender of all of his property to cover not only the original penalties and costs found against him but also for the weekly allowance that had to be paid for his up- keep while in prison. With no records in his name and now no property, Mc- Bride left Sarnia a free but penniless man on 31 March 1858.78 McBride’s experi- ences coloured his perceptions of the world around him and appear to have left him scarred by a deep-seated suspicion of most people, counselling his sons to “Keep your father’s house and home,/ Be not led off to stray and roam/ Where words, sweet sounding, strike the ear;/ Such sweet-lipp’d scoundrels, keep them clear . . .”79 Upon his release from prison, Mc- Bride found employment as a school teacher in Warwick Township, and began his forays into publishing and honing his poetry.80 Like hundreds of others across the province, McBride was captivated by the news of the petroleum boom in the heart of Lambton County at Oil Springs. While the first strike had occurred back in 1858, the first major oil boom began in early 1862. McBride and his sons left Warwick for the oil fields to set up shop along with many other artisans, pro- fessionals, and entrepreneurs. Finding themselves in the centre of a haphaz- ard community of some 1,600 persons amidst a scene of horrendous ecological degradation, the McBride family would soon face another tragedy.81 It was inevi- table that squalid living conditions would engender disease and, by the end of June 1862, one witness explained, “There has been a great deal of Typhoid Fever here whilst I was home. Several have Died.”82 The same correspondent later explained “I think the water is the great cause of it, it is so bad & then there is so much veg- etable matter decomposing in the Woods 77 “Insolvent Debtors Act,” Globe, 7 March 1857; A Doubly Disappointed Settler, “More Land Job- bing!,” Globe, 6 July 1857; “Opinions of the Press: The Next Election,” copied from the Haldimand Inde- pendent in Globe, 10 November 1857. 78 AO, RG 22-2766-0-1 Lambton County, County Court Appearance Book, 1853-1860, 1878, 18. 79McBride, “Lines on the Death of Dog Prince, and his Advice to His Young Masters,” Poems Satirical & Sentimental, 190. 80 Petrolia Advertiser, 21 November 1895; Canada Manuscript Census, 1861, Canada West, Lambton County, Warwick Township, Div. 2, page 8; McBride, Orange Minstrel (1860), cover page. 81 Burr, “‘Oil Mania’: Colonial Land Policy, Land Speculation, and Settlement in Enniskillen Town- ship, 1830s-1860s,” 272. 82 E.W. Watkins, letter of 27 June 1862, to his wife. Archives Western University, Letters of E.W. Wat- inside pages autumn 2013.indd 180 2018-03-03 10:38:12 PM �8�corruption in lambton county, �854-58 around us.”83 Whatever the circumstanc- es, McBride’s eldest son John died in June 1862 at the age of 20. Tragedy would also beset his surviving son, William. He was engaged to marry a local woman who died unexpectedly on a visit with her family in Oakville. The elder McBride recorded both tragic tales in two poems he included in his magnum opus Poems Satirica1 & Sentimental which appeared in 1869. Inconsolable, William never married.84 As of 1870 McBride had stopped publishing his volumes of poetry. How- ever, the following year, in contrast to his apparently more staid and less pedantic neighbours, he informed the census taker for Oil Springs that his occupation was “Poet Writing Poems & Songs on the Evil & good transpiring in Canada.”85 But by then, he had begun to move onto other things. The boom that Oil Springs had enjoyed petered out just as quickly as it had started. The village was left a mere shadow of its former self. Villagers, however, continued to foster hopes and schemes that would see it reemerge from the economic doldrums. McBride’s name was associated with various business dealings that pertained to Oil Springs, such as the Dresden and Oil Springs Railway, and the equally elusive Huron and Erie Railway. Early in 1878, McBride was elected as chaplain of the Lambton Orange Lodge No. 6 in Petrolia.86 Early in 1891, a correspondent to The Cana- dian Bee Journal made note of a recent visit to the McBrides’ oil fields and com- mented at being “astonished to find on the premises about 60 colonies of bees” in the best order. It was his son William McBride, though, who was the real genius behind the honey business and who had sold over fifty dollars in honey the previ- ous year.87 For the most part, the last two decades of Robert McBride’s life remain obscure. Poet, arch-Orangeman, polemi- cist, poet, entrepreneur, debtor, zealot, school teacher, and one time inspector of linens, died on 7 November 1895 at Oil Springs. He was 84. His son duly report- ed the death to local authorities. There had been no attending physician and the cause of death was attributed to “old age.” He is presumably buried in Oil Springs, but his grave is not marked.88 kins to his wife, 1861-1867, M 268. 83 Ibid., letter of 12 September 1862. 84 McBride, “Obituaries,” Poems Satirical & Sentimental, 273 and “William and Susan,” Poems Satiri- cal & Sentimental, 225-26. 85 Canada, 1871 Manuscript Census, Oil Springs, 21. R. McBride. The Canadian Orange Minstrel! For 1870: Written for the Purpose of Keeping in Remembrance the Dark Doings and Designs of Popery in this Country (Toronto: P.H. Stewart, 1870), ii. McBride, “Dissertation,” Poems Satirical & Sentimental, 293- 94. 86 Petrolia Advertiser, 9 October 1874, 19 February 1875, and 11 January 1878. 87 The Canadian Bee Journal, vol. 7, no. 1, 1 April 1891, 472. 88 Ontario Vital Records, Schedule of Deaths, 1895, Oil Springs, 008734, “Robert McBride”. Wil- liam McBride immigrated to the United States in 1907 and ended up in Detroit Michigan. Canada Bor- der Crossings: From Canada to U.S., 1907, Port Huron, 29; 1910 United States Federal Census, Michi- gan, Wayne Co., Detroit City, 1st Ward, 6945. inside pages autumn 2013.indd 181 2018-03-03 10:38:12 PM �82 ONTARIO HISTORY To what extent McBride’s trials and tribulations were due to a conspiracy to punish and silence “[t]his most insulting man” is difficult to say with any certainty. From his own point of view, he was the hapless victim of greedy politicians and a corrupt judiciary that closed ranks when threatened with exposure. Whether he was willing to admit to it, however prin- cipled he believed his stance to have been, the campaign allegedly launched against him had much to do with his dogged refusal to work within the predominant system of quid pro quo that was part and parcel of the political and economic mechanisms of Canada West. His failure to support Malcolm Cameron’s election after having been awarded the position of postmaster did not seal his fate, but it certainly contributed to it. The evidence of McBride’s case that is found in surviv- ing newspapers and court records and the corroboration, albeit one-sided and strongly partisan, provided by his poems gives us a unique glimpse into the inter- actions of the legal system of Lambton County and Canada West as a whole. The poems and their supplementary no- tations as well as McBride’s more prosaic commentaries suggest something about the complex interconnectedness of the political, legal, and land systems. While the claims McBride made are difficult to judge from a distance of 150 years, they do make it clear that personal and politi- cal connections continued to matter. In the end, the poems shed light on the lone figure of McBride himself, an immigrant who was fully engaged in the political process while attempting, in his own way, to improve the lot of his adopted prov- ince. inside pages autumn 2013.indd 182 2018-03-03 10:38:12 PM work_a6dwf2h5bramvbd3igg2vsudk4 ---- wp-p1m-38.ebi.ac.uk Params is empty 404 sys_1000 exception wp-p1m-38.ebi.ac.uk no 221738716 Params is empty 221738716 exception Params is empty 2021/04/06-03:20:37 if (typeof jQuery === "undefined") document.write('[script type="text/javascript" src="/corehtml/pmc/jig/1.14.8/js/jig.min.js"][/script]'.replace(/\[/g,String.fromCharCode(60)).replace(/\]/g,String.fromCharCode(62))); // // // window.name="mainwindow"; .pmc-wm {background:transparent repeat-y top left;background-image:url(/corehtml/pmc/pmcgifs/wm-nobrand.png);background-size: auto, contain} .print-view{display:block} Page not available Reason: The web page address (URL) that you used may be incorrect. Message ID: 221738716 (wp-p1m-38.ebi.ac.uk) Time: 2021/04/06 03:20:37 If you need further help, please send an email to PMC. Include the information from the box above in your message. Otherwise, click on one of the following links to continue using PMC: Search the complete PMC archive. Browse the contents of a specific journal in PMC. Find a specific article by its citation (journal, date, volume, first page, author or article title). http://europepmc.org/abstract/MED/ work_a7kgzsyrgvfd7grqlwalff752a ---- Distributive justice with and without culture This is a repository copy of Distributive justice with and without culture. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/99075/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Jackson, William Anthony orcid.org/0000-0001-5194-7307 (2015) Distributive justice with and without culture. Journal of Cultural Economy. pp. 673-688. ISSN 1753-0369 https://doi.org/10.1080/17530350.2015.1054414 eprints@whiterose.ac.uk https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ Reuse Unless indicated otherwise, fulltext items are protected by copyright with all rights reserved. The copyright exception in section 29 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 allows the making of a single copy solely for the purpose of non-commercial research or private study within the limits of fair dealing. The publisher or other rights-holder may allow further reproduction and re-use of this version - refer to the White Rose Research Online record for this item. Where records identify the publisher as the copyright holder, users can verify any specific terms of use on the publisher’s website. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing eprints@whiterose.ac.uk including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. mailto:eprints@whiterose.ac.uk https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE WITH AND WITHOUT CULTURE William A. Jackson Department of Economics and Related Studies, University of York, York YO10 5DD, UK Email: william.jackson@york.ac.uk Abstract Academic treatments of distributive justice normally adopt a static approach centred on resource allocation among a set of individual agents. The resulting models, expressed in mathematical language, make no allowance for culture, as they never engage with the society’s way of life or the moulding of individuals within society. This paper compares the static approach to distributive justice with a cultural one, arguing that a case for redistribution should rest upon its cultural effects in assisting well-being and social cohesion. Unless we recognise culture, we can have little understanding of why inequalities matter, where they come from, and how they might be reduced. Redistribution may be motivated by universal value judgements taken from external sources, but it also entails internal cultural changes that refashion social relations through cumulative causation. In practical terms, it has to penetrate beyond reallocating resource endowments to bring revised attitudes in a society less tolerant of unequal outcomes. Egalitarian reforms will flourish only if they generate and reflect an egalitarian culture. Keywords: Culture, distributive justice, inequality, egalitarianism, cumulative causation, welfare state mailto:william.jackson@york.ac.uk - 1 - Introduction Equity and equality are much discussed in the academic literature on distributive justice, but from a narrow perspective. Analysis revolves around allocating resources among a set of individual agents: egalitarians would choose a more even allocation over a less even one. To simplify things, inequality is often condensed to one dimension (usually income or wealth) and equitable distribution becomes a cake-dividing puzzle, as if an outside observer could decide on fair shares. The simplified framework facilitates mathematical modelling at the expense of putting distribution within its social and historical context. Omitted from the allocative view of equality is any mention of culture defined as either a way of life or process. Culture as a way of life refers to everyday activities, attitudes and beliefs. Exclusive stress on resource allocation neglects the non-material elements of a way of life, along with the social consequences of inequality. Culture as a process links the individual and social levels to document how the social environment shapes human beings – it deals with what economists would call preference formation. Static models of redistribution assume fixed preferences from the outset with no effort to explain their origin or social background. Important issues are brushed aside: the roots of inequality, how it is perpetuated, how it channels people’s lives, why we care about it, and how we might reduce it. The cultural vacuum shrinks egalitarianism down to an abstract assignment of resources among an atomistic population of individual units. A wider view of equality would recognise culture by looking at a way of life rather than resource allocation and asking how unequal societies come forth. History, cumulative causation and belief systems could then claim their due place in the discussion. If we argue that equality transforms society by fostering social solidarity and communal values, then we make a cultural case for it, where it becomes both cause and effect of changing attitudes. Preferences cannot then be fixed, as the desire for equality turns on how it changes them for the better. Distributive justice branches out beyond an allocation problem. - 2 - Culture as a way of life includes attitudes to inequality held by the general public. A cultural approach should acknowledge everyday notions of justice and injustice that have little to do with academic theories but appear regularly in conversation, opinion polls, voting behaviour and the media. The public may commend inequalities, keep silent about them (thereby tacitly accepting the status quo) or criticise them as being unfair. Much disapproval of inequality is voiced by members of the poor against other poor people thought to have secured small but unjustified advantages; it can be heard in the language of ‘scrounging’, ‘free-riding’, ‘getting something for nothing’, ‘workers versus shirkers’ and ‘strivers versus skivers’. Similar disapproval could be directed against the rich, especially those with inherited wealth and unearned incomes, although the complaints tend to be rarer and more muted. Popular sentiments about inequality yield an informal, bottom-up brand of distributive justice that stands beside the top-down, academic brand. The present paper examines the significance of culture for distributive justice, formal or informal. It begins by looking in further detail at the static, culture-free approach, before moving on to alternative, culturally based arguments and locating them within a different theoretical framework. The last two sections consider the practical implications of a culturally sensitive viewpoint and draw general conclusions. Distributive justice without culture Academic debates on distributive justice are apt to treat it as a topic in analytical philosophy – the aim is to find logical decision rules to allocate resources optimally among individual agents typically modelled as rational utility maximisers with fixed preferences (Roemer, 1996; Sen, 1997; Moulin, 2003). The individualistic method addresses inequalities among individuals but pays less attention to social classes, structures or institutions, which are secondary and noticed only if they impinge on distribution at the individual level. Since analysis takes place inside a single period, redistribution would have to be a one-shot - 3 - reallocation of resource endowments. Nothing is said about how the current allocation emerged, why it has persisted or how it might evolve: assessment is hemmed within a timeless, artificial realm. Value judgements in the Benthamite, utilitarian tradition would select individual utilities as the yardstick of welfare and maximise the sum of utilities over the whole population to achieve the highest possible total. This may not be egalitarian, for it values total utility regardless of distribution and awards priority to agents who produce the most utility from given resources (Sen, 1997, Chapter 1). Equality would be optimal only if everybody had the same utility function with diminishing marginal utility; otherwise the optimum is unequal and may endorse discrimination against the sick, disabled, elderly, etc. A greater degree of egalitarianism requires a concave objective function that values even distributions of utility above uneven ones – the more concave, the more egalitarian (Moulin, 2003, Chapter 3). Judgements are made first about the utility distribution and then, through utilities, about the distribution of incomes and other resources. As with individual preferences, the origin of egalitarian values passes unremarked and we are not told why we should want equality or how we could attain it. Distributive justice based solely on utilities (‘welfarism’) has obvious drawbacks: utility is poorly defined and not directly observable, may be an unreliable indicator of well-being, and may not represent rational behaviour. Critics of welfarism from within the static perspective have proposed adding non-utility information into welfare assessments so as to supplement or replace utility: Sen’s capability approach, for example, replaces utility with the capability to function and participate in social activities (Sen, 1993). Non-utility information offsets the pre-eminence of utilities and creates space for social determinants of personal capabilities. The capability approach is essentially individualistic, however, and says little about culture, social structures or ways of life (Jackson, 2005; Dean, 2009; Sayer, 2012). In order to get further away from welfarism, one needs a deeper account of culture and social context. The static perspective follows the linear sequence in Figure 1. At the starting point comes distributional information on incomes, goods and other resources. Under welfarism, this must filter through individual preferences before social welfare can be assessed, introducing - 4 - utilities as another stage in the sequence. Any case for redistribution comes from basic value judgements about the distribution of utilities. The external source of the values leads to a fact/value split in which a ‘positive’ analysis of resource allocation is transmuted into a ‘normative’ blueprint for redistribution when values are appended. Both individual preferences and basic value judgements stay fixed and distinct from each other, without interaction or historical development. In non-welfarist variants of the static perspective, non-utility information can enter directly into welfare assessments that reach beyond utilities alone (Sen, 1982, Part IV). The ethics remain individualistic, because value judgements still rest on individuals, as against social structures, classes or other groups. Adherence to the linear sequence gives the literature on distributive justice a strong family resemblance, even though it is portrayed as a series of welfarist and non-welfarist alternatives. Figure 1: Static distributive justice Positive Normative Basic value judgements Income, Individual utilities Social welfare Egalitarianism goods, etc. Non-utility information Figure 1 lends itself to mathematical expression but cannot readily accommodate culture as a way of life or process. Ethics are separated from the past and future to be collapsed into a - 5 - technical problem of maximising an objective function for an anonymous bunch of individuals at a single, unspecified time. The individualistic method and dearth of social structures mirrors how orthodox economic theory has become desocialised (Jackson, 2013). Social influences on the individual are at best implicit, playing no overt part in the analysis, and ethics must hinge on individual welfare. Culture as a process, whereby individual preferences are formed within society, would swap the linearity of Figure 1 for circularity that permits backward causation from the social to the individual. A cultural outlook demands an alternative vision awake to the social formation of preferences and values. Cultural arguments for equality Disquiet about static, ahistorical theorising has long been voiced, dating back to the onset of utilitarianism and classical economics in the early nineteenth century. Criticism came from writers in the Romantic tradition who focused on the neglect of history and culture in economic theorising (Ryan, 1981; Löwy, 1987; Löwy and Sayre, 2001; Connell, 2001; Jackson, 2009, Chapter 3). They saw economists as promulgating mechanistic theories that erased the human life from economics and condoned the harsh social conditions bred by early capitalism. Many of these critics were prominent literary authors and commentators (including Edmund Burke, William Blake, Samuel Taylor Coleridge, William Cobbett, Thomas Carlyle, Charles Dickens, Elizabeth Gaskell, John Ruskin and Matthew Arnold), but they stood outside the economics profession and had little sway over the practice of economics. Few of them are regarded as egalitarians – their ideal was often to have benevolent, paternalistic leadership rather than equality. The cultural critiques do not preclude a case for equality, though, and can be turned in that direction. An early statement of the cultural arguments for equality was made by Matthew Arnold in his 1878 essay Equality (Arnold, 1986). Equality, for Arnold, is to be valued not as an abstract principle or natural right but for its contribution to social cohesion and the - 6 - complexion of everyday life. A society marked by extreme inequalities of income, wealth and status loses the shared interests and experiences needed to forge common values and friendship among all individuals and groups. Social divisions are institutionalised into a permanent hierarchy with adverse effects on both rich and poor. The rich, enjoying inherited fortunes, are spoiled from birth, relieved of any constructive social purpose, flattered and pampered by ingrained deference, and subject to the temptations proffered by idleness and lavish material wealth. The poor face difficulties of subsistence, lack the material and social advantages possessed by their fellow citizens, find themselves at the bottom of the hierarchy, and become excluded from full participation in society. Social divisions when established are taken for granted in what Arnold termed a ‘religion of inequality’. Beliefs supportive of the status quo enter the national culture, thus legitimising the social order and suppressing debate over reforms. The questions raised by Arnold were discussed at length by R.H. Tawney in his classic book Equality, first published in 1931 (Tawney, 1964). As an economic historian he was attuned to cultural thought, having stressed how cultural and religious values guided capitalist economic development (Tawney, 1920, 1926). Inequality, in Tawney’s view, can never just be about uneven distribution of resources or asymmetries among specialised economic functions: these are at the core of inequality but far from the whole picture. Enquiry must extend beyond the material dimension to embrace the social structure of a society, as well as its beliefs and values. An unequal society is unequal not only in its resource allocation but in its social roles, personal relationships and attitudes – various dimensions are entwined to make up a generalised hierarchy reproduced across generations. The dominant values justify inequality and confirm it as the natural order, so the only route to greater equality is to challenge them and loosen their grip. If they endure, then progress towards equality will be modest at best and prone to counter-attack. Within economics, the role of culture in preserving inequalities has been emphasised by institutionalist writers (Galbraith, 1992; Stanfield, 1995; Dugger, 1996; Zafirovski, 2000; Brinkman and Brinkman, 2005; Streeck, 2011). Pivotal here are the ‘enabling myths’ that rationalise disparities in income and status, asserting that people receive their due rewards and should be happy with inequality (Dugger, 1998, 2000). Privileged elites supposedly - 7 - deserve their good fortune through their superior abilities, skills, intellect and knowledge. The poor merit their lowly status because they lack the talents, enterprise and application essential for success: they are the culprits of their own misfortune in a fair world. Lower social classes will be more likely to go along with the status quo if they can be persuaded to defer to the upper classes and try to emulate them. Spread throughout a society, these attitudes ratify a hierarchical way of life. The privileged rest at ease, sure that their conspicuous wealth and consumption will be accepted and even admired by the mass of people below – what Thorstein Veblen termed the ‘leisure class’ lives at a standard miles above the average without having to work and without having its idleness queried (Veblen, 1899). Hierarchies built into social attitudes cannot be dismantled at a stroke by redistributive measures; as products of culture they can be removed only through cultural change. Egalitarianism has to take us from a culture of enabling myths to one that cherishes equality and rejects social divisions. Outside economics, the cultural aspects of inequality have been highlighted by recent social theory, with the work of Pierre Bourdieu as the exemplar (Swartz, 1977, 1997, Chapter 8; Savage, 2000, Chapter 5; Crompton, 2008, Chapter 6). For Bourdieu, inequalities in culture sustain and legitimise inequalities in income or wealth: economic capital is accompanied by other kinds of capital (social, cultural, symbolic) that have parallel inequalities (Bourdieu, 2002). Privileged social classes are sanctioned by property ownership but cement their status through their cultural milieu, which gives access to the arts and plenty of free time for artistic connoisseurship. Cultural inequalities can be replicated by informal means, even when education is formally open and meritocratic (Bourdieu and Passeron, 1990). Teaching people about the arts would disseminate knowledge but would not tear down the cultural walls between classes. Unequal distribution of cultural capital finds an outlet in consumer tastes that take on a layered quality delineated by social hierarchies (Bourdieu, 1984). Bourdieu’s work on consumption has affinities with Veblen’s institutional economics, exploring the class divisions in consumer behaviour and the inducements for ordinary people to covet the lifestyle of the rich (Campbell, 1995; Rosenbaum, 1999; Bögenhold, 2001; Trigg, 2001; Shipman, 2004). Consumption acquires symbolic value over and above any value in fulfilling material needs, so theories dwelling on the material - 8 - dimension will be blinkered. A true understanding of inequality must deal with its numerous interrelated dimensions and how it has been socially constructed. Common features of the cultural arguments The writers who have discussed inequality from a cultural viewpoint belong to no single movement and advocate no single theory; they are scattered across academic disciplines, some standing outside academia, and cannot be categorised as a school of thought. They nonetheless share ideas that distinguish them from the egalitarianism put forward in static notions of distributive justice. Without wanting to play down the differences, one can summarise common features: Multidimensionality - Cultural arguments for equality apply to a society’s way of life, not the allocation of incomes and other resources. Several dimensions are involved, so it is impossible to reduce inequalities to a single, measurable scale. Welfare assessment must go beyond selecting the ‘right’ dimension (utility, income, goods, etc.). Social structures - Appraising social structures is fundamental to a cultural approach. Egalitarian arguments make little sense if they overlook how individuals are socialised into a hierarchical, structured way of life (culture as a process). Ideology - Unequal arrangements are defended by an ideology that depicts them as inevitable and banishes more equal alternatives (enabling myths, a religion of inequality). The ideology purports to be self-evident and impervious to serious criticism, a distillation of eternal realities. Preference formation - Beliefs that encourage acquiescence in an unequal society will change individual behaviour. Preferences should not be viewed as fixed, and the origin of - 9 - beliefs should be considered. A population brought up to abide by inequalities will actively participate in their reproduction. Adverse effects on the individual - Long-standing inequalities harm all individuals, both rich and poor, and damage their social relationships. The rich become selfish, arrogant and complacent in the assurance that their advantages are warranted, as are the disadvantages of those beneath them. The poor become segregated, listless, resigned to their fate but perhaps envious of their superiors and aspiring to join the rich. Adverse effects on society - Inequality yields a less cohesive and harmonious society. Lower classes, excluded from participation in social activities, will feel alienated. Upper classes, facing the resentment of the poor, will retreat into their own social circles and stay as far from the poor as they can. Instead of being cohesive, society will fragment into separate, sometimes antagonistic groups. Power and authority - Culture as a way of life incorporates the asymmetrical power and authority that maintain inequalities and block attempts at reform. Reallocating resources is necessary but insufficient for greater equality, which depends on recasting institutions and reducing tolerance of big disparities in economic and social power. Internalised values - From a cultural perspective, egalitarian values cannot merely be tacked on to an otherwise value-free analysis. Values that influence behaviour will have to be internalised into the culture. A quest for equality must emerge through cultural change, even if it is not unique to the society and originates in universal value judgements. Cumulative causation - Cultural changes occur in historical time, subject to cumulative causation. Whenever inequalities are established, they will increase through economies of scale, competitive advantage, concentrated power and property inheritance. Egalitarianism must seek to reverse the cumulative trends, creating a virtuous circle of greater equality. Outcomes not opportunities - Arguments for equality of opportunity are too weak to generate an egalitarian culture. Under equal opportunities, people have the same life chances - 10 - but may ‘choose’ unequal outcomes that are deemed acceptable. A thoroughgoing egalitarianism should have a desire for equal outcomes at the forefront of social attitudes. Distributive justice with culture The cultural arguments for equality see it as more than a trait of a population of individuals, given that it changes people’s behaviour and aids their relationships. If we are to acknowledge how preferences are formed and how values persist within the ongoing social context, we need a non-reductionist social theory that encompasses agency-structure interaction: individual agents can then be shaped within society and social structures produced and reproduced through individual agency (see, for example, Bourdieu, 1977 and Giddens, 1984). Similar social theories are set out by critical realist writers, who avoid reductionism and pay heed to culture and agency-structure interaction when making assumptions about the nature of reality (Bhaskar, 1979; Archer, 1995, 1996; Lawson, 1997, Part III). A non-reductionist stance implies that Figure 1 must be inadequate, as it omits social structures and imposes fixed individual preferences as the arbitrary basis for value judgements. Once social structures are a level of analysis in their own right, coeval with the individual level, methodological individualism is ruled out. Values may not be concerned only with individual states but with personal relationships, group interests and social cohesion. Egalitarianism becomes a circular process of cultivating and preserving values woven into the fabric of society. Figure 2 shows the resulting theoretical framework. At the heart lies the interplay of agency and structure augmented by egalitarian values, such that the wish for equality impresses upon current behaviour and institutions: agency upholds egalitarian values, while social structures embody egalitarian reforms. Basic value judgements may still enter from outside as the catalyst for the internal forces driving egalitarianism. Practical benefits - 11 - emanate on the right of Figure 2 in a more cohesive, less divided society and a more even distribution of incomes, capabilities and other outcomes. Figure 2: Cultural versions of distributive justice Egalitarian reforms Social structures Social cohesion Basic value judgements Individual incomes, Egalitarian values Individual agents capabilities, etc. Unlike the linear sequence of Figure 1, egalitarianism in Figure 2 is a self-reinforcing process occurring in historical time. The case for equality, if it is to have practical success, must be absorbed into values and reproduced through cultural transmission. As soon as the relevant values enter the culture, the positive/normative barrier breaks down, with basic value judgements no longer inserted at a late stage into a positive analysis. Values bearing on social conditions must be present within the society and not limited to a hypothetical assessor. Internalisation of values stops short of moral relativism that abandons universal principles and treats each society as morally unique. From a relativistic angle, societies differ in their values with no presumption in favour of equality – Figure 2 could be adapted to inegalitarian values and reforms. Unequal societies have their enabling myths that justify inequality and - 12 - spread the associated values as widely as possible among the public. A generic case for equality has to include cross-cultural values external to the societies under consideration. Many of the cultural arguments summarised above are global and proclaim the benefits of greater equality at any time or place. They appeal to culture but keep away from relativism that might be neutral towards distribution. Absolute arguments for equality are supported by the recent empirical literature that examines the effects of inequality on health and well-being (Hagerty, 2000; O’Connell, 2004; Neckerman and Torche, 2007; Phelan, Link and Tehranifar, 2010; Wilkinson and Pickett, 2010; Oishi, Kesebir and Diener, 2011; Cooper, McCausland and Theodossiou, 2013, 2015). The main finding is that more equal societies fare better on a range of welfare criteria, irrespective of local variations in culture and institutions. Basic value judgements making a universal case for equality can be introduced from outside a society, as in Figure 2, and then call forth an egalitarian culture within the society. External in origin, they must percolate through the culture before they can influence behaviour. Being circular, Figure 2 has no starting or finishing point. Nor does its circularity go in one direction – this can vary according to how we interpret things. Suppose, for example, that we begin with individual agents at the lower right-hand side of Figure 2. In the agency-structure relation the initial causal thrust is upward and causality seems anti-clockwise: individual agents reproduce social structures, which preserve egalitarian reforms, which help to sustain egalitarian values, which impact upon individual agency and preferences. Causality comes full circle and starts all over again. Suppose, on the other hand, that we begin with social structures at the upper right-hand side of Figure 2. Now the initial causal thrust is downward and causality seems clockwise: social structures mould individual agents, who have egalitarian values, which promote egalitarian reforms, which alter social structures. Causality again comes full circle but this time in the opposite direction. The complex, two-way interaction means that motion can be perceived as going either way: an individualistic interpretation suggests anti-clockwise motion, a structural interpretation clockwise. Figure 2 entails neither individualistic nor structural reductionism, and the two circular motions are equivalent. - 13 - The ethics in Figure 2, thanks to their avoidance of individualistic reductionism, are not confined to comparisons among individuals. In a circular process of cultural reproduction we cannot pick out fixed individual preferences as the foundation for allocative decisions. Basic value judgements enter into the circular causality that determines the society’s way of life. Without an individualistic benchmark, egalitarian values are released from the obligation to boil everything down to the individual level and can embrace factors other than individual welfare. Judgements can be made directly about social structures and relationships: ethics can evaluate social hierarchies, power, work organisation and family arrangements. Individual welfare loses its monopoly on how social outcomes are judged, and appraisal of structural context comes into play. Neither individual nor structural levels have ethical sovereignty. Figure 2 does not compel us to choose among income, utility and other dimensions, an issue that preoccupies much of the standard literature on distributive justice. The urge to have one dimension comes from the desire to quantify welfare on a single scale. A cultural approach deals with a society’s way of life that comprises various dimensions, none of which has supremacy – electing to operate on a single one would be misguided. Material resources are not exhaustive in the assessment of welfare. Social justice should venture beyond distribution of material resources to take in cultural matters such as social inclusiveness, status differences and recognition of minority groups (Fraser, 1995, 2003; Sayer, 2005; Lister, 2007). Multiple strands of inequality can exist in themselves without being weighted and combined into an overall welfare score. It remains useful to measure inequalities in income, wealth, etc., and empirical studies retain their importance, though immeasurable dimensions of inequality should also be given due attention. The theory in Figure 2 is stratified, with at least two levels of analysis – individual agents and social structures – that are irreducible to each other. Inequalities pertain not only to persons but to impersonal roles and positions within firms, government, the media and other institutions. Power concentrated among a few owners or managers will determine the working environment and have repercussions for society. A thoroughgoing egalitarianism must be alert to roles and positions as well as personal circumstances – the two are bound together, and sole emphasis on the personal level will be futile in curtailing inequality. - 14 - Structured relations among social classes and other groupings lead to asymmetries of property ownership, social/cultural capital and power. If huge inequalities are embedded in social structures, then the chances of greater equality at the personal level are minimal. Egalitarianism has to stretch across many levels of analysis and include structural inequalities within its remit. Practical implications Although analyses of distributive justice are frequently ahistorical, the likelihood is that we are discussing a modern capitalist economy defined by private ownership of capital and ubiquitous markets for labour and finance. Capitalism exists in several varieties, but they all approve of private capital accumulation as the vehicle for economic development. Simultaneously with the amassing of private capital comes the rise in private property incomes and wealth, with burgeoning inequality when wage incomes lag behind. A capitalist economy, left unchecked, sponsors income and wealth gaps that get ever bigger and do not converge on a balanced equilibrium (Wade, 2004; Rigney, 2010, Chapter 3; Piketty, 2014). The gaps become institutionalised and justified by the culture, in the inegalitarian counterpart of Figure 2. While the poor lose out, they are encouraged to be satisfied with any real income gains from economic growth or ambitions to join the rich. Inegalitarian attitudes do seem to have thrived lately, for the ballooning inequalities in developed countries have been accepted by the general public and not met with widespread opposition (Horton and Bamfield, 2009; Kelly and Enns, 2010; Unwin, 2013, Chapter 3; Shildrick and McDonald, 2013). Whether or not the public actually support inequality, they have been willing to comply with trends that benefit the rich and hurt the poor. The lack of visible concern gives the impression that the rich somehow deserve their rewards, even though the reasons for this are seldom clarified (Rowlingson and Connor, 2011; Sachweh, 2012). In a culture accustomed to income and wealth accumulation, perceptions of inequality - 15 - will be dulled or biased and people may underestimate its extent (Norton and Ariely, 2011; Cruces, Perez-Truglia and Tetaz, 2013). Any push towards progressive redistribution will happen only when attitudes swing back to egalitarianism. Pursuit of equality within a capitalist economy is possible but faces an uphill task. The role of the state will be crucial if ambiguous. As Karl Polanyi pointed out, the state created capitalism (contrary to libertarian doctrines about spontaneous markets) and introduced welfare measures afterwards in order to soften its sharp edges – state planning gazed first and foremost on markets rather than social policies (Polanyi, 1944). Radical and Marxian writers have been sceptical of state activity under capitalism and viewed the welfare state as a palliative that makes concessions to workers’ interests but serves to legitimise the economic system (Gough, 1979; Mishra, 1981, Chapter 5; Offe, 1984; Pierson, 2006, Chapter 2). Less sceptical were R.H. Tawney and Richard Titmuss, who saw the welfare state as a motor of social and cultural change with genuine transformative capacity (Reisman, 1982, Part II, 2001; Alcock et al., 2001, Part 3; Deacon, 2002, Chapter 1). Given the political will and democratic mandate, the state could implement a ‘strategy of equality’, in other words a comprehensive programme of measures designed to curb disparities of income and wealth (Tawney, 1964, Chapter IV). Components of such a strategy would include welfare benefits, progressive taxation, socialised health care and education, subsidised public utilities, full employment policies, new types of property ownership, and reforms to the organisation of work. As it unfolded, the strategy would gather momentum through the cumulative causation in Figure 2, which would halt and reverse the inegalitarian tendencies of laissez-faire capitalism. Recent income trends in developed countries hint at both the feasibility of redistributive measures and the obstacles to them. Empirical evidence divides into two contrasting periods: from the 1940s to the 1970s the personal income distribution became more equal and inequality measures fell, whereas from the 1980s onwards the inequality measures have risen as personal incomes have become more unequal (Caminada and Goudswaard, 2001; Alderson and Nielsen, 2002; Brandolini and Smeeding, 2009; McCall and Percheski, 2010; Atkinson, Piketty and Saez, 2011). Factor incomes display a similar pattern, with a rising wage share of national income until the 1970s, followed by a falling wage share ever since (Kristal, 2010; - 16 - Wolff, 2010). The earlier trend towards equality coincided with expansion of the welfare state during the post-war decades and high employment guaranteed by Keynesianism. It demonstrated that, despite the capitalist environment, egalitarian policies can succeed. The reversal of trend coincided with the turn to neo-liberalism from the 1980s, which brought welfare retrenchment, withdrawal of progressive taxation, privatisation of public services and utilities, deregulation of finance, deflationary macroeconomic policies, and rejection of the Keynesian commitment to full employment (Glyn, 2006; Irvin, 2008). Neo-liberalism has restored the inegalitarian counterpart of Figure 2, supplanting egalitarian values and reforms with inegalitarian ones. Even the financial crisis prompted only marginal adjustments rather than a search for alternatives, and the surrounding culture stays intact (Allon and Redden, 2012; Glynos, Klimecki and Willmott, 2012). Conventional wisdom is comfortable with enormous personal incomes, coupled with individualistic attitudes that spurn social cohesion and collective identity. Attempts to regain the path of greater equality would have to slow down and reverse cumulative changes propelling the economy in the other direction. Cumulative causation is self-reinforcing and never ends of its own accord – to stop it requires some outside agency or event to intrude and disturb the circle (Skott, 1994; Berger, 2009; Pluta, 2010). A renewed trend towards equality will come about only through dedicated government policies, a prospect that seems distant in today’s political climate but might ultimately be provoked by the widening gulf between rich and poor. Part of a new strategy of equality would be to revive the welfare measures and progressive taxation weakened under neo-liberalism. Tawney was aware that these policies on their own are insufficient for an egalitarian redrawing of society – they are vital to any strategy of equality but fail to tackle the causes of inequality in the private sector (Martin, 1982; Elliott and Clark, 1989). Stalwart egalitarianism cannot afford to ignore a private sector that authorises vast discrepancies in income and status: it would have to open out control of industry, give employees more clout over their working lives, and redress gross imbalances of power. Marketisation and commodification would have to be resisted, leaving room for decommodification that bolsters non-market sectors of the economy (Williams, 2005, Part III; Vail, 2010). In the long-term vision of Tawney and Titmuss, the gradual spread of an egalitarian culture could underpin evolutionary transformation towards a more cooperative, less competitive society. At the - 17 - moment this vision appears over-optimistic, but it still offers the best hope for attaining greater equality within a capitalist economy. Conclusion Static concepts of distributive justice, which dominate the academic literature on the subject, are hampered by their neglect of culture. When expressed in mathematical models, distribution becomes a timeless allocation problem, as if an omniscient ethical advisor could step up and reallocate resources to ensure fair shares. Such ahistorical, non-cultural theory has little truck with the social consequences of inequality and, indeed, says nothing about why we might be egalitarians. The result is a sterile exercise in meeting an objective that could quite as easily be inegalitarian. It remains unclear how the chosen resource allocation could be reached, especially if it differs dramatically from the current one. The political ramifications of reassigning property rights are sidestepped, and the cultural aspects of inequality are absent from the theoretical models. Belying its apparently rigorous treatment, distributive justice shrivels into a one-dimensional mode adopted chiefly for analytical convenience. Greater equality will occur only with a shift away from the ideology of laissez-faire capitalism, which tolerates and even celebrates inequalities. Other belief systems, less tolerant of inequality, can be found in social democracy, socialism, communism, Marxism and so forth. Egalitarianism in a capitalist economy could be carried out through progressive redistributive measures and social policies but would need a switch from neo-liberalism back to the social democratic values that held sway during the mid-twentieth century. Stronger forms of egalitarianism that query the unequal property ownership under capitalism could not be brought to fruition in a capitalist economy. Marxian views, for example, would dismiss private ownership of the means of production as being inherently exploitative and argue for non-capitalist alternatives with different property relations based on socialist or communist - 18 - guidelines. These political matters lie beyond the scope of the present paper, but they illustrate the importance of culture and belief systems for enacting social change. A cultural approach to distributive justice has two major advantages worth reiterating. The first is that it can supply a proper rationale for egalitarianism by pondering the cultural effects of inequality. Arguments for equality must explain why a more equal society is better than a less equal one, and the case has to invoke culture as a process – equality is desirable because it can improve the well-being and behaviour of every member of society and strengthen social relationships. People who are equal have more in common with each other and develop greater social harmony than they would if divided by large income and other gaps. These arguments are impossible in a static model where individual preferences are fixed and the case for equality relies on external value judgements: a reshuffle of resource endowments would leave people unchanged, the only gain being a higher score on an objective function, whatever that may mean. If culture goes unmentioned, then the grounds for egalitarianism will be hazy. The second advantage is that a cultural approach can address the cultural transmission of inequality. Social divisions must have had historical origins – inequalities in income are tied to inequalities in social position and bound up with beliefs and attitudes. Long-standing disparities in income, status and power have been applauded by a culture of inequality and are perpetuated through that culture. With cumulative causation, a society that welcomes inequalities will watch them grow as wealth becomes concentrated. Egalitarian reform is not just about changing resource endowments but about reversing the social and cultural pressures towards inequality. An absolute appeal for distributive justice can be introduced from outside but, if it is to change things, must have some purchase on the culture. Equality would not then be imposed against the grain by central government but would permeate the cultural atmosphere at all levels and among all organisations: social symmetries would be preserved through reproduction of existing arrangements. No longer an external goal, equality would be internalised as the norm. Egalitarianism can prevail only if it becomes enshrined in social attitudes and gets passed on to future generations as a culture of equality. - 19 - REFERENCES ALCOCK, P., GLENNERSTER, H., OAKLEY, A. & SINFIELD, A. (eds) (2001) Welfare and Wellbeing: Richard Titmuss’s Contribution to Social Policy, Bristol, Policy Press. ALDERSON, A.S. & NIELSEN, F. (2002) ‘Globalization and the great U-turn: income inequality trends in 16 OECD countries’, American Journal of Sociology, vol. 107, no. 5, pp. 1244-1299. ALLON, F. & REDDEN, G. (2012) ‘The global financial crisis and the culture of continual growth’, Journal of Cultural Economy, vol. 5, no. 4, pp. 375-390. ARCHER, M.S. (1995) Realist Social Theory: The Morphogenetic Approach, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. ARCHER, M.S. (1996) Culture and Agency: The Place of Culture in Social Theory, revised edition, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. ARNOLD, M. (1986) ‘Equality’, in Matthew Arnold: A Critical Edition of the Major Works, eds M. ALLOTT & R.H. SUPER, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 432-455. ATKINSON, A.B., PIKETTY, T. & SAEZ, E. (2011) ‘Top incomes in the long run of history’, Journal of Economic Literature, vol. 49, no. 1, pp. 3-71. BERGER, S. (ed) (2009) The Foundations of Non-Equilibrium Economics: The Principle of Circular and Cumulative Causation, London, Routledge. BHASKAR, R. (1979) The Possibility of Naturalism: A Philosophic Critique of the Contemporary Human Sciences, Brighton, Harvester Press. BÖGENHOLD, D. (2001) ‘Social inequality and the sociology of life style: material and cultural aspects of social stratification’, American Journal of Economics and Sociology, vol. 60, no. 4, pp. 829-847. BOURDIEU, P. (1977) Outline of a Theory of Practice, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. BOURDIEU, P. (1984) Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgement of Taste, London, Routledge and Kegan Paul. BOURDIEU, P. (2002) ‘The forms of capital’, in Readings in Economic Sociology, ed N.W. BIGGART, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 280-291. - 20 - BOURDIEU, P. & PASSERON, J.-C. (1990) Reproduction in Education, Society and Culture, 2nd edn, London, Sage. BRANDOLINI, A. & SMEEDING, T.M. (2009) ‘Income inequality in richer and OECD countries’, in The Oxford Handbook of Economic Inequality, eds SALVERDA, W., NOLAN, B. & SMEEDING, T.M., Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 71-100. BRINKMAN, R.L & BRINKMAN, J.E. (2005) ‘Cultural lag: a relevant framework for social justice’, International Journal of Social Economics, vol. 32, no. 3, pp. 228-248. CAMINADA, K. & GOUDSWAARD, K. (2001) ‘International trends in income inequality and social policy’, International Tax and Public Finance, vol. 8, no. 4, pp. 395-415. CAMPBELL, C. (1995) ‘The sociology of consumption’, in Acknowledging Consumption: A Review of New Studies, ed D. MILLER, London: Routledge, pp. 95-124. CONNELL, P. (2001) Romanticism, Economics, and the Question of ‘Culture’, Oxford, Oxford University Press. COOPER, D., McCAUSLAND, W.D. & THEODOSSIOU, I. (2013) ‘Income inequality and wellbeing: the plight of the poor and the curse of permanent inequality’, Journal of Economic Issues, vol. 47, no. 4, pp. 939-957. COOPER, D., McCAUSLAND, W.D. & THEODOSSIOU, I. (2015) ‘Is unemployment and low income harmful to health? Evidence from Britain’, Review of Social Economy, vol. 73, no. 1, pp. 34-60. CROMPTON, R. (2008) Class and Stratification, 3rd edn, Cambridge, Polity Press. CRUCES, G., PEREZ-TRUGLIA, R. & TETAZ, M. (2013) ‘Biased perceptions of income distribution and preferences for redistribution: evidence from a survey experiment’, Journal of Public Economics, no. 98, pp. 100-112. DEACON, A. (2002) Perspectives on Welfare: Ideas, Ideologies and Policy Debates, Buckingham, Open University Press. DEAN, H. (2009) ‘Critiquing capabilities: the distractions of a beguiling concept’, Critical Social Policy, vol. 29, no. 2, pp. 261-278. DUGGER, W.M. (ed) (1996) Inequality: Radical Institutionalist Views on Race, Gender, Class, and Nation, Westport, CT, Greenwood Press. DUGGER, W.M. (1998) ‘Against inequality’, Journal of Economic Issues, vol. 32, no.2, pp. 286-303. - 21 - DUGGER, W.M. (2000) ‘Deception and inequality: the enabling myth concept’, in Capitalism, Socialism, and Radical Political Economy, ed R. POLLIN, Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, pp. 66-80. ELLIOTT, J.E. & CLARK, B.S. (1989) ‘Richard Henry Tawney on the democratic economy’, International Journal of Social Economics, vo. 16, no. 3, pp. 44-58. FRASER, N. (1995) ‘From redistribution to recognition? Dilemmas of justice in a “post-socialist” age’, New Left Review, vol. 212, pp. 68-93. FRASER, N. (2003) ‘Social justice in the age of identity politics: redistribution, recognition, and participation’, in Redistribution or Recognition? A Political-Philosophical Exchange, eds N. FRASER & A. HONNETH, London: Verso, pp. 7-109. GALBRAITH, J.K. (1992) The Culture of Contentment, Boston, Houghton Mifflin. GIDDENS, A. (1984) The Constitution of Society: Outline of the Theory of Structuration, Cambridge, Polity Press. GLYN, A. (2006) Capitalism Unleashed: Finance, Globalization, and Welfare, Oxford, Oxford University Press. GLYNOS, J., KLIMECKI, R. & WILLMOTT, H. (2012) ‘Cooling out the marks: the ideology and politics of the financial crisis’, Journal of Cultural Economy, vol. 5, no. 3, pp. 297-320. GOUGH, I. (1979) The Political Economy of the Welfare State, London, Macmillan. HAGERTY, M. R. (2000) ‘Social comparisons of income in one’s community: evidence from national surveys of income and happiness’, Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, vol. 78, no. 4, pp. 764-771. HORTON, T. & BAMFIELD, L. (2009) Understanding Attitudes to Tackling Inequality, York, Joseph Rowntree Foundation. IRVIN, G. (2008) Super Rich: The Rise of Inequality in Britain and the United States, Cambridge, Polity Press. JACKSON, W.A. (2005) ‘Capabilities, culture and social structure’, Review of Social Economy, vol. 63, no. 1, pp. 101-124. JACKSON, W.A. (2009) Economics, Culture and Social Theory, Cheltenham, Edward Elgar. JACKSON, W.A. (2013) ‘The desocialising of economic theory’, International Journal of Social Economics, vol. 40, no. 9, pp. 809-825. - 22 - KELLY, N.J. & ENNS, P.K. (2010) ‘Inequality and the dynamics of public opinion: the self-reinforcing link between economic inequality and mass preferences’, American Journal of Political Science, vol. 54, no. 4, pp. 855-870. KRISTAL, T. (2010) ‘Good times, bad times: postwar labor’s share of national income in capitalist democracies’, American Sociological Review, vol. 75, no. 5, pp. 729-763. LAWSON, T. (1997) Economics and Reality, London, Routledge. LISTER, R. (2007) ‘Social justice: meanings and politics’, Benefits, vol. 15, no. 2, pp. 113-125. LÖWY, M. (1987) ‘The Romantic and the Marxist critique of modern civilization’, Theory and Society, vol. 16, no. 6, pp. 891-904. LÖWY, M. & SAYRE, R. (2001) Romanticism against the Tide of Modernity, Durham, NC, Duke University Press. MARTIN, D.A. (1982) ‘R.H. Tawney as political economist’, Journal of Economic Issues, vol. 16, no. 2, pp. 535-543. McCALL, L. & PERCHESKI, C. (2010) ‘Income inequality: new trends and research directions’, Annual Review of Sociology, vol. 36, pp. 329-347. MISHRA, R. (1981) Society and Social Policy: Theoretical Perspectives on Welfare, London, Macmillan. MOULIN, H.J. (2003) Fair Division and Collective Welfare, Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. NECKERMAN, K.M. & TORCHE, F. (2007) ‘Inequality: causes and consequences’, Annual Review of Sociology, vol. 33, pp. 335-357. NORTON, M.I. & ARIELY, D. (2011) ‘Building a better America – one wealth quintile at a time’, Perspectives on Psychological Science, vol. 6, no. 1, pp. 9-12. O’CONNELL, M. (2004) ‘Fairly satisfied: economic equality, wealth and satisfaction’, Journal of Economic Psychology, vol. 25, no. 3, pp. 297-305. OFFE, C. (1984) Contradictions of the Welfare State, London, Hutchinson. OISHI, S., KESEBIR, S. & DIENER, E. (2011) ‘Income inequality and happiness’, Psychological Science, vol. 22, no. 9, pp. 1095-1100. PHELAN, J.C., LINK, B.G. & TEHRANIFAR, P. (2010) ‘Social conditions as fundamental causes of health inequalities: theory, evidence, and policy implications’, Journal of Health and Social Behavior, vol. 51(S), pp. S28-S40. - 23 - PIERSON, C. (2006) Beyond the Welfare State? The New Political Economy of Welfare, 3rd edn, Cambridge, Polity Press. PIKETTY, T. (2014) Capital in the Twenty-First Century, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. PLUTA, J.E. (2010) ‘Evolutionary alternatives to equilibrium economics: some suggested applications’, American Journal of Economics and Sociology, vol. 69, no. 4, pp. 1155-1177. POLANYI, K. (1944) The Great Transformation: The Political and Economic Origins of Our Time, New York, Farrar and Rinehart. REISMAN, D.A. (1982) State and Welfare: Tawney, Galbraith and Adam Smith, London, Macmillan. REISMAN, D.A. (2001) Richard Titmuss: Welfare and Society, 2nd edn, Basingstoke, Palgrave. RIGNEY, D. (2010) The Matthew Effect: How Advantage Begets Further Advantage, New York, Columbia University Press. ROEMER, J.E. (1996) Theories of Distributive Justice, Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. ROSENBAUM, E.F. (1999) ‘Against naïve materialism: culture, consumption and the causes of inequality’, Cambridge Journal of Economics, vol. 23, no. 3, pp. 317-336. ROWLINGSON, K. & CONNOR, S. (2011) ‘The “deserving rich”? Inequality, morality and social policy’, Journal of Social Policy, vol. 40, no. 3, pp. 437-452. RYAN, C.C. (1981) ‘The fiends of commerce: Romantic and Marxist criticisms of classical political economy’, History of Political Economy, vol. 13, no. 1, pp. 80-94. SACHWEH, P. (2012) ‘The moral economy of inequality: popular views on income differentiation, poverty and wealth’, Socio-Economic Review, vol. 10, no. 3, pp. 419-445. SAVAGE, M. (2000), Class Analysis and Social Transformation, Buckingham, Open University Press. SAYER, A. (2005) ‘Class, moral worth and recognition’, Sociology, vol. 39, no. 5, 947-963. SAYER, A. (2012) ‘Capabilities, contributive injustice and unequal divisions of labour’, Journal of Human Development and Capabilities, vol. 13, no. 4, pp. 580-596. SEN, A.K. (1982) Choice, Welfare and Measurement, Oxford, Basil Blackwell. - 24 - SEN, A.K. (1993) ‘Capability and well-being’, in The Quality of Life, eds M.C. NUSSBAUM & A.K. SEN, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 30-53. SEN, A.K. (1997) On Economic Inequality, 2nd edn, Oxford, Oxford University Press. SHILDRICK, T. & MACDONALD, R. (2013) ‘Poverty talk: how people experiencing poverty deny their poverty and why they blame the “poor”’, The Sociological Review, vol. 61, no. 2, pp. 285-303. SHIPMAN, A. (2004) ‘Lauding the leisure class: symbolic content and conspicuous consumption’, Review of Social Economy, vol. 62, no. 3, pp. 277-289. SKOTT, P. (1994) ‘Cumulative causation’, in The Elgar Companion to Institutional and Evolutionary Economics, eds G.M. HODGSON, W.J. SAMUELS & M.R. TOOL, Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, pp. 119-124. STANFIELD, J.R. (1995) Economics, Power and Culture: Essays in the Development of Radical Institutionalism, London, Macmillan. STREECK, W. (2011) ‘Taking capitalism seriously: towards an institutionalist approach to contemporary political economy’, Socio-Economic Review, vol. 9, no. 1, pp. 137-167. SWARTZ, D. (1977) ‘Pierre Bourdieu: the cultural transmission of social inequality’, Harvard Educational Review, vol. 47, no. 4, pp. 545-555. SWARTZ, D. (1997) Culture and Power: The Sociology of Pierre Bourdieu, Chicago, University of Chicago Press. TAWNEY, R.H. (1920) The Acquisitive Society, New York, Harcourt, Brace and Howe. TAWNEY, R.H. (1926) Religion and the Rise of Capitalism, London, Murray. TAWNEY, R.H. (1964) Equality, London, George Allen and Unwin. TRIGG, A.B. (2001) ‘Veblen, Bourdieu, and conspicuous consumption’, Journal of Economic Issues, vol. 35, no. 1, pp. 99-115. UNWIN, J. (2013) Why Fight Poverty?, London, London Publishing Partnership. VAIL, J. (2010) ‘Decommodification and egalitarian political economy’, Politics and Society, vol. 38, no. 3, pp. 310-346. VEBLEN, T. (1899) The Theory of the Leisure Class: An Economic Study of Institutions, New York, Macmillan. WADE, R.H. (2004) ‘On the causes of increasing world poverty and inequality, or why the Matthew effect prevails’, New Political Economy, vol. 9, no. 2, pp. 163-188. - 25 - WILKINSON, R.G. & PICKETT, K.E. (2010) The Spirit Level: Why Equality is Better for Everyone, London, Penguin. WILLIAMS, C.C. (2005) A Commodified World? Mapping the Limits of Capitalism, London, Zed Books. WOLFF, E.N. (2010) ‘Rising profitability and the middle class squeeze’, Science and Society, vol. 74, no. 3, pp. 429-449. ZAFIROVSKI, M.Z. (2000) ‘Economic distribution as a social process’, Social Science Journal, vol. 37, no. 3, pp. 423-443. work_ac4uep5fd5cvjbkpscuoumcqdu ---- © Journal of Mediation and Applied Conflict Analysis, 2019, Vol. 6, No. 1 http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie Page | 743 Narrative practices in restorative justice Judit Hajdu Abstract This paper gives a description of methodologies, practices and principles of narrative practices and an overview of restorative practices as a foundation for a suggested combination of the two approaches in dealing with criminal incidents. It notes similarities between the two approaches, including the importance of stories, involvement of communities and individuals in their own conflicts, rejection of blame, searching the broader social landscape for explanation and influence and acknowledging and accepting contradictory stories. The author sees the two movements as coming from different directions but occupying overlapping territories and identifies — two areas where combined use of the two approaches could be beneficial — at the interface between restorative justice and the courts and in the role of communities in restorative justice practice. It concludes with an invitation to practitioners to test the ideas for cross-fertilisation outlined in the article and to develop programmes that draw from both sets of practices for the benefit of victims, offenders and communities. Introduction I had been practising Narrative Therapy for families and couples and doing divorce mediations for a few years when I started working with prisoners and first encountered restorative practices. I was immediately struck by similarities between narrative methods and restorative practices and was sure I would see a great deal of liaison between them. To my surprise, I have encountered few instances of inclination to consider co-operation among narrative practitioners, http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie/ © Journal of Mediation and Applied Conflict Analysis, 2019, Vol. 6, No. 1 http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie Page | 744 and almost none in the field of restorative justice. As I started my training in restorative practices, I often felt an urge to include the well-structured scaffoldings of questions and interviews so characteristic of narrative practices into our exercises, and found they fitted in well even though they were not familiar to my tutors. I was encouraged to explore the possibilities of utilising a synthesis of restorative and narrative practices in criminal cases. The acceptance and use of restorative and narrative practices have been gaining ground over the past few decades and the principles and methodologies of each method are becoming well-established. In primary and secondary schools, as well as in higher education, the two approaches have been usefully blended (Winslade and Kecskemeti, 2016; Winslade and Williams, 2012; Kecskemeti, 2013; Kecskemeti, et al., 2013; Ganem and Duncan, 2017; Walgrave, 2011) and it is my belief that the two practices could gain considerably from a more extensive alliance in other areas, especially criminal justice. Narrative practices — some history and areas of use Narrative therapy was developed by David Epston of New Zealand and Michael White of Australia in the 1980s (White and Epston, 1992; Denborough, 2008; Denborough et al., 2008). Their collaboration was rooted in anthropology, family therapy and Eriksonian hypnotherapy and created not only a new approach but a new paradigm in psychotherapy and, ultimately, in mediation and collective practices. Narrative approaches, as will be discussed in more detail later, have always viewed individuals in relation to their social environment. Narrative practitioners work extensively with communities that endure hardship or have experienced trauma and in a close collaboration with them they have designed collective narrative practices that have been used effectively all over the world — for example, among prisoners, refugees, war survivors and other trauma victims (Denborough, 2008; Denborough et al., 2008). Mediation has also been developed http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie/ © Journal of Mediation and Applied Conflict Analysis, 2019, Vol. 6, No. 1 http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie Page | 745 in narrative practices to influence family counselling, divorce mediation and conflict resolution in health and educational settings (Winslade and Monk, 2000). The narrative metaphor Breaking away from the prevailing psychotherapy practices, narrative therapy does not assume an underlying dysfunction that defines the behaviour of people, but is concerned with the meaning-making processes, the way people organise events of their lives into stories and the way, in turn, these same stories determine their actions (White and Epston, 1990). When people come to therapy they are usually not content with their stories. They do not want to continue to live their lives in line with them. Their problems are overwhelming and control their lives. They live problem-saturated stories. The task of the narrative practitioner is to sharpen their ears to alternative stories, events that do not fit the dominant storyline, the ones that had not been strung together into stories and could contradict the self-defining ones. These events are called unique outcomes, actions on the part of the client that can be starting points in weaving alternative stories to live by (White and Epston, 1990). These unique actions are the occasions, so often brushed aside as exception not worthy of attention, when, for example, Anger could not drive a father into verbal and physical aggression against his son upon hearing bad news from school, or when Fear could not coerce the son into cheating or running away. These alternative stories are fragile at the beginning and are constantly in danger of being defeated by dominant ones, so every effort should be made to “thicken” the thin stories (Morgan, 2000) by giving minute details of the scene, the smell, the colours and feelings. Telling and re-telling the stories make them sturdier, while writing them down also contributes to a thick storyline. The aim, however, is not to simply replace the dominant, problem- saturated stories with the desirable alternative ones, but instead to widen the landscape to encourage a rainbow of possible stories in place of the narrow http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie/ © Journal of Mediation and Applied Conflict Analysis, 2019, Vol. 6, No. 1 http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie Page | 746 perspective created by the problem. A multi-storied perspective opens space for negotiating a number of possible outcomes that were previously unthinkable. Deconstructing discourses White’s philosophy was influenced by feminist authors and by the writings of Michel Foucault (Payne, 2006). He was intrigued by the ethics of power and the way it manifests itself in social discourses, in the taken-for-granted truths of institutions, religions, professions, clubs, neighbours and family members in all the strata of our lives. In any culture or society some stories have more power, more weight, than others. These cultural stories or discourses demarcate the lives and accepted behaviour of citizens, who perceive them as ‘facts’ or ‘reality’ (Freedman & Combs, 2002). These norms and narratives can be in contradiction. The masculine narrative of real-men-do-all-they-can-for-their-loved-ones can be in serious conflict with society’s demand to respect property. So many men have been incarcerated for taking up crime to provide for their families, especially in dire situations like serious health problems. Cultural discourses within smaller communities could also generate personal dilemmas. For example, the strict prison code of NTA (Never Trust Anyone) is against the strong desire and need to belong to somebody and have friendships to sustain integrity in hardship. Our lives are full of these dilemmas and discrepancies. Consider the traditional religious beliefs versus the demands of a modern woman or the dilemma between cultural integration and maintaining a homogeneous family unit. Assisting clients to identify and describe these many dominant narratives (voices) is one of the main tasks of the practitioner. Only by doing so can she or he select the ones worthy of attention in any setting (Winslade & Monk, 2000). Once the discourse becomes evident, it is possible to deconstruct, analyse and reconsider the nature and impact of this narrative. http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie/ © Journal of Mediation and Applied Conflict Analysis, 2019, Vol. 6, No. 1 http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie Page | 747 Deconstructing the dominant social discourses is the first step to liberate oneself from their power. Historically, psychology, and especially psychotherapy, have been complicit in maintaining and even strengthening these discourses. Narrative practices question them first by acknowledging their presence and second by purposefully seeking out and reflecting on marginalised or alternative narratives. In practice, it means that practitioners acknowledge that they cannot be completely neutral in their dealings and that the client knows more about their own life (White, 1995). Discourses affect individual lives as well as professional beliefs. It is, for instance, a strong social narrative of the mediation profession that people are driven by their needs and the clash of these needs result in conflicts. Thus, according to the problem-solving approach in mediation, therapists must be “neutral” and “impartial” to negotiate between these needs (Winslade, et al., 1998). Winslade and Monk, mediators whose practices are informed by narrative ideas, criticise both the problem-solving approach of mediation practices and the need for — not to mention the possibility of — neutrality and impartiality on the part of practitioners. Winslade and Monk have developed a new conflict paradigm (Winslade & Monk, 2000). They have moved towards a notion that conflicts are embedded within differences of social discourses. According to a social constructionist view, there is no single true version of an event, only different perspectives. People make meaning of the world according to their experiences, which inevitably vary, and these meanings form the stories they tell about any event. These distinct stories, and the meanings given to them, are unique and therefore unavoidably create the potential for conflict (Winslade & Monk, 2000). This shift in perspective liberates the conflicting parties from their fixation on the problem itself, thus providing the opportunity for understanding the larger social context. The process of deconstructing their respective narratives helps them to reconsider how they view themselves and the other (Winslade & Monk, 2000). For example, once a divorced father realises that acting as the ‘traditional http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie/ © Journal of Mediation and Applied Conflict Analysis, 2019, Vol. 6, No. 1 http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie Page | 748 head of the family’ is not the only or best way to pass on his values to his son, he can see himself engaging in a meaningful relationship with his child. As a result, time spent together can become more significant to each of them. This shift may in turn change his relationship with his ex-partner. Externalisation Since the 18th century the notion of internalised problems has become the norm; we refer to people as bad-tempered, shy, weak, or aggressive as a complete description of their personalities and behaviours. The person becomes an object, a mere container of problems. These problems are difficult to solve and require the knowledge and skills of an expert. The problem-solving process will be long and the outcome hard to predict (White, 1995). Narrative therapy, however, rejects the attempt to locate the problem within the person. Michael White’s most-quoted maxim is “The person is not the problem, the problem is the problem” (White, 1988/9; White & Epston, 1990). Adhering to this maxim, the therapeutic conversation is conducted in a way that problems get externalised, personified and talked about as if from a distance. Externalising conversations has a unique language in which problems to be objectified are used in their noun form instead of as adjectives. Narrative practitioners talk about “the anger” rather than “angry” to personify the problems and so give them intentions and power of their own. Problems can be talked of as vicious, evil or just mischievous, detached from the disputing parties, almost like creatures that make people’s lives difficult. Naming the problem is a process that tempers their impact on the people and reduces the intensity of the conflict. In fact, this could be the first agreement in addressing a conflict, bringing a measure of unity without the threat of having to give up positions. Having established a common name for the disagreement, there is an opportunity to explore its history and its effects on the relationship http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie/ © Journal of Mediation and Applied Conflict Analysis, 2019, Vol. 6, No. 1 http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie Page | 749 between the parties. Practitioners can ask questions about what the problem or conflict destroys, hinders, makes difficult or even what it makes possible (Winslade & Monk, 2000). Talking, for instance, about jealousy, as a monster that destroys intimacy, ruins the best moments, and brings about anger and desperation, makes it easier to talk about its effects without accusation and the consequent defensiveness. Also, jealousy not only affects the person one is jealous about, but the jealous person as well. It might whisper irrational things into her or his ear or distract the person at work. By inviting jealousy into the therapy room, it is easier to face it together, help overcome its toxic effect, and see the other person and the relationship without its devastating control. It should be noted, however, that, externalisation is not merely a technique, it is an attitude, a way of looking at the world. The aim is to see the problem separate from and not as defining the person. Working with a family with a history of abuse, for instance, the therapist might inquire about the “reign of aggression”, the “debilitating power of fear” or the “deceiving nature of silence”. Conducting the therapeutic conversation with this mindset, parties come to understand the effect a problem might have on others and determine how to confront and resolve the problem (Freeman, et al., 1997). Let me give you a short excerpt from a family consultation: Father (about his young adult son, who is in trouble for vandalism): I can understand him. I was like him. It runs in the family. When I was his age I smashed and broke and saw no God no Human. Like an animal. Like a man. Practitioner: You mean, it was difficult to control your anger? F: It was no anger. It was like a wild beast. But sure, it was difficult to control. It’s in me. I am that beast… Less so now. P: How is that? How can you control that wild beast more these days? F: Dunno. I suppose I got older, wiser … maybe tired … and suppose, I just can’t. Not with the little one (his grandson) around. I’ve got to look after him. Can’t let him down. http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie/ © Journal of Mediation and Applied Conflict Analysis, 2019, Vol. 6, No. 1 http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie Page | 750 P: So, you think it might be love or responsibility that could put the rein on that wild beast. F: Those for sure. Mother: (turning to her son) I could see no wild beast in your eyes. Son: Maybe you don’t, but I feel it… The practitioner could have chosen to initiate a conversation about the story or narrative of what it is to be a man because that is part of how the father understands his son. Instead, she chose to externalise the idea of anger. She initiated a name to encourage the christening and carried on with the externalising language. It struck a chord with the son, who could feel understood, but still responsible. It opened up the possibility of considering the skills and knowledges that could help him control his own beast. Much later, having externalised the notions of anger, responsibility and tenderness, it was easier to discuss the social expectations (narrative) of masculinity. Collective narrative practices Narrative therapy has also turned away from the practice of isolating people with problems. Recognising that problems are embedded in the culture, a narrative approach involves members of the relevant communities to support the process. In collective practices, it is paramount “to listen for both individual and collective speech patterns” (Denborough, 2008 p23): whenever there is trauma there is always a social issue. Practitioners therefore respond to both the individual and the collective issues. In their view, attending to a greater social problem often plays a considerable part in healing the individual (Denborough, 2008). For instance, in the comment: “When I was a kid, I was never much regarded as a human being in my family. I was a girl and fathers, of course, want boys” it is possible to detect the personal story of the speaker’s role in her family as well as the collective, the social discourse, of ‘boys being more valuable’ than http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie/ © Journal of Mediation and Applied Conflict Analysis, 2019, Vol. 6, No. 1 http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie Page | 751 girls. Bringing the collective into focus can be genuinely empowering (Denborough, 2008). Narrative practices, although part of a therapy tradition, demonstrate the extraordinary potential of engaging the community — the collective — in addressing an individual problem. This — the community — is the very place where restorative practices take their roots. Restorative practices — some history In ancient times, the practice of victims and offenders settling their disputes with help from their community was widespread. Crime was not considered an act against society. These cultures acknowledged that the participants — victims, offenders, their families and their immediate communities — were all affected by the crime and therefore must be involved in restitution. This is not to say that there were no rules to compensate for wrongdoings, but the aim of these rules was to reclaim an atmosphere of peace, wholeness and companionship in the community. Codes of Hammurabi, Roman Law, German tribal laws or the traditions of indigenous people of North America, New Zealand and Australia were all similar in that they were less punitive than restorative (Van Ness & Strong, 2010). As kingdoms replaced tribal cultures, rulers took the place of victims; crimes were committed against the ‘crown’. Punishment was meted out by the ruler and restitution or fines were paid to the state. The real victims were left out of the process. Although the failures of the system became apparent and prison reformers tried repentance, work treatment, training, psychological and mental treatments of the offenders, the victims were never again thought worthy of including (Van Ness & Strong, 2010). It was not until the 1960s and ’70s that victim rights groups began to mobilise. Nils Christie, a Norwegian criminologist, considered criminal acts as conflicts and thus unavoidable elements of society. He argued that these http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie/ © Journal of Mediation and Applied Conflict Analysis, 2019, Vol. 6, No. 1 http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie Page | 752 behaviours should be cherished, their solutions should not be monopolised by institutions, but rather be given back to the parties in conflict (Christie, 1977), an idea that is compatible with the perception of conflict as “the almost inevitable by-product of diversity” (Winslade & Monk, 2000, p. 41). Winslade and Monk also want to give back the conflict to the participants by encouraging them to name it, make meaning of it, realise and deconstruct the social discourses giving the conflict its strength. Christie (1977) called for the de-institutionalising of criminology; not unlike narrative theorists urging practitioners to step aside as experts and encourage individuals and communities to take responsibility for addressing problems. He described his vision of a victim-oriented criminal system that takes its format after neighbourhood courts, a system where response to crime is decided by those who are most closely affected by it and governed by the values of the community. Soon research and experiments resulted in the introduction of interventions premised on the understanding of “crime as a wound within the community and recognise(s) that justice requires not just accountability but also healing” (Umbreit & Armour, 2011). Restorative Justice as it evolved is not a scheme or a set of techniques but – much the same as Narrative practices – a world view, a perspective on human contact and especially conflict (Umbreit & Armour, 2011). It is a dynamic and often controversial domain of beliefs and practices trying to find its way between being part of the system of law and justice and a social movement (Walgrave, 2011). Restorative justice programmes The three principal restorative justice initiatives are victim-offender mediation (VOM), conferencing and circles. The four essential values of all restorative justice programmes are: • Inclusion — making sure that all affected parties are included (victims, offenders, their respective families and the larger community). http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie/ © Journal of Mediation and Applied Conflict Analysis, 2019, Vol. 6, No. 1 http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie Page | 753 • Encounter — a face-to-face meeting of the participants in a secure environment (when and where it is feasible); • Amends — the offender taking responsibility for harm done and for restitution or compensation; and • Reintegration — providing an opportunity for those responsible for causing harm to return to the community (Van Ness & Strong, 2010). VOMs are guided face-to-face meetings between victims and offenders — and maybe the support persons of both parties — in a safe setting after thorough preparation by the facilitator. The name is somewhat misleading as the aim of the encounter is not — as is true in most mediation interventions — to come to a consensus acceptable by both parties. Instead, the process provides an opportunity for reconciliation, where victims gain confidence over their vulnerability and find a measure of acceptance and peace, and offenders realise the full effect of their behaviour and accept responsibility for the impact of their actions. An ideal outcome of VOM is not necessarily compensation or restitution but psychological changes in the victim and the offender in relation to the criminal act. The story of the crime can be re-authored by the participants to create a narrative that is coherent and reflects their new perspectives on the events of the crime. Family conferencing was first introduced in New Zealand to save young offenders from prison and is now widely used in several countries. The principal goal of this process is to preventing the criminalisation of vulnerable youth. The offender’s extended family, together with other willing community members, are invited to discuss and determine how to share tasks and responsibilities that address the offender’s behaviour, pooling their resources. Experts are not part of the conference but can be asked to provide answers to questions from group members to assist the group in making decisions. Circles are facilitated discussions about harm or conflicts concerning a community. They can be held after sentencing to aid reconciliation (peace-making http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie/ © Journal of Mediation and Applied Conflict Analysis, 2019, Vol. 6, No. 1 http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie Page | 754 circles) or in place of sentencing (sentencing circles). In recognition of traditional methods, some judicial decisions in Canada have been transferred to traditional first nation communities (Bradshaw & Roseborough, 2005). A possible synergy Narrative and restorative practices share common principles as well as some history: • importance of stories; • rejecting the expert position of professionals; • significance of communities; • inviting communities and individuals to own their conflicts and stories; • relying on the wisdom of traditional cultures in problem-solving; • rejecting blaming the individual and searching the broader social landscape for explanation and influence; • acknowledging the simultaneous existence of contradictory stories and accepting them; and • seeing conflict as essential, something that can have value. Restorative justice aims for justice that entails healing, while narrative therapy “has the capacity to channel the energy arising from individual troubles and shape it into productive social action” (McLeod, 2006, p. 207). Thus, combining the two movements, that come from two directions and occupy overlapping territories could intensify their effect. There are two areas where use of a combination of restorative and narrative practices could be beneficial to both approaches. http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie/ © Journal of Mediation and Applied Conflict Analysis, 2019, Vol. 6, No. 1 http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie Page | 755 1) Interface between restorative justice and the criminal justice system Most restorative justice programmes take place within the court context. Thus, it is no surprise that it has been strongly influenced by the values and practices of the legal system, leaving little room for alternative outcomes apart from apology, disclosure and amends. Offenders’ stories are often labelled “comfort stories” by practitioners, meaning they are formed to make excuses to ameliorate responsibility (Booth, 2018), while victims’ stories are also often limited to satisfy social beliefs about victimhood (Pemberton et all, 2018). Jenkins (2009), who combines restorative and narrative ideas in his work with men who have abused, encourages practitioners to challenge the initial, often one-sided, self-deprecatory or self-important abusive self-narratives of the offenders and listen for signs of ethical qualities which they can use as openings to develop a fuller, multi-storied narrative less governed by the often-confining social discourses of masculinity (Jenkins, 2006). The danger of accepting culturally constructed narratives — those deemed consistent with the norms of the legal system — as the only truth about a person, applies to victims’ stories as well. Narratives of offenders and victims are connected by the stories of crime, but the meanings of crime differ considerably for victims, offenders and the legal system (Decraemer, 2014). Complying with norms of criminal justice can result in one-sided storylines that emphasise vulnerability and guilt, leaving little room for self-definition or strength. It is the responsibility of the practitioner to find the unique outcomes that can lead to alternative stories and provide space for therapeutic change (White, 2007). Whether offenders and victims can share their stories, and when, should be decided by the practitioner in consultation with all affected parties. Victim- offender mediation commonly starts with thorough preparation performed in alternating separate meetings with the victim(s) and the offender(s). The aim of the preparatory phase is to build trust with the mediator and the process, http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie/ © Journal of Mediation and Applied Conflict Analysis, 2019, Vol. 6, No. 1 http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie Page | 756 decrease anxiety and prepare the participants to see, hear or simply be in the presence of the other (Mercer & Madsen, 2015). Narrative techniques could be considered in this preparatory phase. As part of the narrative process, the participants could discuss and negotiate the meaning of experiences such as pain, loss, and violence. In the process of deconstructing these terms, the victim and offender can revise the isolating discourses and thereby assert a measure of control over their stories. With thorough preparation, there is every possibility that it can turn out to be a life-changing event. 2) The role of communities in restorative justice practice In restorative justice, community members play a variety of roles, including the active and direct involvement of immediate family members of victims and offenders, concerned community members at peace-making circles, and the dedicated work of volunteers (Rossner & Bruce, 2016). I argue that restorative justice as a movement, as well as a form of practice, could benefit largely from the tested and proven methods of collective narrative practices. One of their many advantages is that they rely on the strengths, traditions and cultural norms of the communities themselves. The underlining principle of collective practices is the importance of telling and re-telling of life-stories — the narratives that create the ever-changing identities of persons. Re-authoring culturally defined stories needs audiences, stories need to be told and heard and then they can be profoundly life-changing (White, 2007). The first narrative technique that used audiences to absorb and respond to stories is outsider witness practice, which is rooted in the work of American anthropologist Barbara Myerhoff: “Definitional ceremonies deal with the problems of invisibility and marginality; they are strategies that provide opportunities for being seen and in one’s own terms, garnering witnesses to one’s worth, vitality, and being.” (Myerhoff 1982, p.267) http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie/ © Journal of Mediation and Applied Conflict Analysis, 2019, Vol. 6, No. 1 http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie Page | 757 Outsider witness practices build on the power of acknowledgment. The highly-structured ritual is divided into three stages: 1. Telling of the life-story by the person the ceremony is organised for; 2. Reflection in response to this story by the witnesses — by answering specific questions; and 3. Reflection by the person the ceremony is organised for, on how his or her story influenced the witnesses. Outsider witnessing is a widely-used technique not just in community work but in therapy or mediation and it could be a powerful tool in the hands of restorative practitioners in the aftermath of harm done to the community. Other collective practices can be used, such as sharing stories of knowledge and achievements between communities, the ‘tree of life’ technique that uses the metaphor of the tree to find and build on the roots and strength of communities experiencing hardship, the ‘collective timelines’ technique to highlight shared sentiments between people of very different backgrounds, and the power of song- writing and music. These methods have been developed in a variety of cases and used when crime or incarceration affected a community (Denborough, 2008). Conclusion This article identified many similarities in the underlining principles of narrative and restorative practices and suggested ways of combining the two practices in criminal cases. Narrative techniques and methodologies that could be used within the framework of restorative justice include externalisation, spotting unique outcomes to weave alternative stories, re-authoring stories to gain multi-storied identities, and a great variety of collective narrative practices that could enhance the effectiveness of restorative justice. Narrative practitioners on the other hand http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie/ © Journal of Mediation and Applied Conflict Analysis, 2019, Vol. 6, No. 1 http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie Page | 758 could venture more in the territory of restorative practices — especially in criminal cases in judicial settings. Greater awareness of the similarities between the two approaches is needed and could be achieved, in part at least, through conference and journal contributions from both sides. I urge restorative and narrative practitioners to test the ideas for cross-fertilisation outlined in this article and to develop programmes drawing on both sets of practices for the benefit of victims, offenders and communities. References Booth, M. (2018) in a blog of the film Injustice (http://www.injustice- film.com/2018/06/23/michaela-booth-on-victims-and-redemption/) Bradshaw, W. & Roseborough, D. (2005) Restorative justice dialogue: The Impact of Mediation and Conferencing on Juvenile Recidivism, Federal Probation, 69(2), p. 15–21. Available at: http://ir.stthomas.edu/ssw_pub/24 (Accessed: 15 May 2018) Christie, N. (1977) Conflicts as property, The British Journal of Criminology, 17(1): 1-15. Decraemer, K. (2014) Working with (Young) Offenders, Conference notes, Third Europe+ Conference of Narrative Therapy and Community Work, Iasi, Romania Denborough, D. (2008) Collective Narrative Practice – Responding to Individuals, Groups and Communities who have Experienced Trauma, Adelaide: Dulwich Centre Publications. Denborough, D., J. Freedman, and C. White (2008) Strengthening resistance: The use of narrative practices in working with genocide survivors, Adelaide: Dulwich Centre Foundation. Freedman, J., and G. Combs (2002) Narrative therapy with couples ... and a whole lot more! Adelaide, S. Aust.: Dulwich Centre Publications. Freeman, J. C, D. Epston, D. Lobovits (1997) Playful Approaches to Serious Problems: Narrative Therapy with Children and Their Families, New York: W.W. Norton. http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie/ http://www.injustice-film.com/2018/06/23/michaela-booth-on-victims-and-redemption/) http://www.injustice-film.com/2018/06/23/michaela-booth-on-victims-and-redemption/) http://ir.stthomas.edu/ssw_pub/24 http://www.narrativetherapylibrary.com/strengthening-resistance-the-use-of-narrative-practices-in-responding-to-genocide-survivors.html http://www.narrativetherapylibrary.com/strengthening-resistance-the-use-of-narrative-practices-in-responding-to-genocide-survivors.html © Journal of Mediation and Applied Conflict Analysis, 2019, Vol. 6, No. 1 http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie Page | 759 Ganem P., D. Duncan (2017) Integrative Restorative Justice Narrative Mediation circle Approach: Students’ Perspective of their MSW Program Experience, Available at: https://csus- dspace.calstate.edu/bitstream/handle/10211.3/189850/GanemDuncanRJNMcThesi s.pdf?sequence=1 Jenkins, A. (2006) Shame, Realisation and Restitution: The Ethics of Restorative Practice, Australian and New Zealand Journal of Family Therapy, 27(3), p. 153– 162. Jenkins, A. (2009) Becoming Ethical: A Parallel, Political Journey with Men who have Abused, Dorset: Russel House Publishing. Kecskemeti, M. (2013) Competent Students and Caring teachers: is a Good Pedagogy Always the Best Pedagogy? Teachers and Curriculum, Vol.13: 93-98. Kecskemeti, M., K. Kaveney, S. Gray, W. Drewery (2013), A Deconstructive Approach to Class Meetings: Managing Conflict and Building Communities, Narrative and Conflict: Explorations in Theory and Practice 1(1): 30- 51. McLeod, J. (2006) Narrative thinking and the emergence of postpsychological therapies, Narrative Inquiry. 16(2006) pp. 201-210. Mercer, V., K. Sten Madsen, M. Keenan and E. Zinsstag (2015) Sexual Violence and Restorative Justice: A Practice Guide, Leuven Institute of Criminology. [online] Available at: http://www.euforumrj.org/wp-content/uploads/2015/09/Doing- Restorative-justice-in-cases-of-sexual-violence_practice-guide_Sept2015-1.pdf (Accessed: 15 May 2018) Morgan, A. (2000) What is Narrative Therapy? An Easy-to-read Introduction, Adelaide, S. Australia: Dulwich Centre Publications. Myerhoff, B (1980) Number Our Days, New York: Simon and Schuster. Myerhoff, B. (1982) ‘Life history among the elderly: Performance, visibility, and remembering’ in Ruby J. (ed.) A crack in the mirror: Reflexive perspective in anthropology, Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press. Payne, M (2006) Narrative Therapy, Sage Publications. Pemberton, A., P.GM. Aarten, E. Mulder (2018) Stories as property: Narrative ownership as a key concept in victims’ experiences with criminal justice, Criminology and Criminal Justice [online]. Available at: http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie/ https://csus-dspace.calstate.edu/bitstream/handle/10211.3/189850/GanemDuncanRJNMcThesis.pdf?sequence=1 https://csus-dspace.calstate.edu/bitstream/handle/10211.3/189850/GanemDuncanRJNMcThesis.pdf?sequence=1 https://csus-dspace.calstate.edu/bitstream/handle/10211.3/189850/GanemDuncanRJNMcThesis.pdf?sequence=1 http://www.euforumrj.org/wp-content/uploads/2015/09/Doing-restorative-justice-in-cases-of-sexual-violence_practice-guide_Sept2015-1.pdf http://www.euforumrj.org/wp-content/uploads/2015/09/Doing-restorative-justice-in-cases-of-sexual-violence_practice-guide_Sept2015-1.pdf © Journal of Mediation and Applied Conflict Analysis, 2019, Vol. 6, No. 1 http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie Page | 760 http://journals.sagepub.com/doi/10.1177/1748895818778320 (Accessed: 15 May 2018) Rossner, M and Bruce, J. (2016) Community participation in restorative justice: rituals, reintegration, and quasi-professionalization, Victims & Offenders, 11(1) pp. 1-19. [online] Available at: http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/65067/ (Accessed: 15 May 2018) Umbreit, M., M. P. Armour (2011) Restorative Justice Dialogue: An Essential Guide for Research and Practice, New York: Springer Publishing Company. Van Ness D.W., K. H. Strong (2010) Restoring Justice: An Introduction to Restorative Justice, Routledge. Walgrave, L. (2011) Investigating the Potentials of Restorative Justice Practice, Journal of Law & Policy 36 [online]. Available at: https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/law_journal_law_policy/vol36/iss1/6/ (Accessed: 15 May 2018) White, M. (1988/9) The externalizing of the problem and the re-authoring of lives and relationships in White M. (ed.) Selected Papers, Adelaide, Australia: Dulwich Centre Publications. White, M., D. Epston (1990) Narrative Means to Therapeutic Ends, New York: Norton. White, M., D. Epston (1992) Experience, contradiction, narrative and imagination: Selected papers of David Epston and Michael White 1989-1991, Adelaide: Dulwich Centre Publications. White, M. (1995) Re-authoring lives, Adelaide: Dulwich Centre Publications. White, M. (2007) Maps of Narrative Practice, New York: Norton. Winslade, J., M. Kecskemeti (2016) Better Classroom Relationships, New Zealand: NZCERPRESS. Winslade, J., G. Monk, A. Cotter (1998) A Narrative Approach to the Practice of Mediation, Negotiation Journal, 14(1), pp. 21-41 Winslade, J., G. Monk (2000) Narrative Mediation: A New Approach to Conflict Resolution, San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. Winslade, J., M. Williams (2012) Safe and Peaceful Schools: Addressing Conflict and Eliminating Violence, Corwin. http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie/ http://journals.sagepub.com/doi/10.1177/1748895818778320 http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/65067/ https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/law_journal_law_policy/vol36/iss1/6/ © Journal of Mediation and Applied Conflict Analysis, 2019, Vol. 6, No. 1 http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie Page | 761 Judit Hajdu has been working as a psychologist with children, adults, couples and families for 15 years. She has been secretary to the Hungarian Family Therapy Association and has worked as psychologist and restorative practitioner at prisons. She was the initiator of prison radio in Hungary. At present, she studies criminology at the University of Glasgow. http://jmaca.maynoothuniversity.ie/ Narrative practices in restorative justice Judit Hajdu Narrative therapy was developed by David Epston of New Zealand and Michael White of Australia in the 1980s (White and Epston, 1992; Denborough, 2008; Denborough et al., 2008). Their collaboration was rooted in anthropology, family therapy and Eriksoni... The narrative metaphor Deconstructing discourses Externalisation Collective narrative practices Restorative practices — some history Restorative justice programmes A possible synergy Narrative and restorative practices share common principles as well as some history:  importance of stories;  rejecting the expert position of professionals;  significance of communities;  inviting communities and individuals to own their conflicts and stories;  relying on the wisdom of traditional cultures in problem-solving;  rejecting blaming the individual and searching the broader social landscape for explanation and influence;  acknowledging the simultaneous existence of contradictory stories and accepting them; and  seeing conflict as essential, something that can have value. Restorative justice aims for justice that entails healing, while narrative therapy “has the capacity to channel the energy arising from individual troubles and shape it into productive social action” (McLeod, 2006, p. 207). Thus, combining the two mov... There are two areas where use of a combination of restorative and narrative practices could be beneficial to both approaches. 1) Interface between restorative justice and the criminal justice system Most restorative justice programmes take place within the court context. Thus, it is no surprise that it has been strongly influenced by the values and practices of the legal system, leaving little room for alternative outcomes apart from apology, dis... Jenkins (2009), who combines restorative and narrative ideas in his work with men who have abused, encourages practitioners to challenge the initial, often one-sided, self-deprecatory or self-important abusive self-narratives of the offenders and list... The danger of accepting culturally constructed narratives — those deemed consistent with the norms of the legal system — as the only truth about a person, applies to victims’ stories as well. Narratives of offenders and victims are connected by the st... 2) The role of communities in restorative justice practice References Booth, M. (2018) in a blog of the film Injustice (38TUhttp://www.injustice-film.com/2018/06/23/michaela-booth-on-victims-and-redemption/)U38T White, M. (2007) Maps of Narrative Practice, New York: Norton. work_acjxmlbwafbylkf3smmsqtxiau ---- Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 U.S. Department of Justice Office of Justice Programs Bureau of Justice Statistics BJS Mandatory P.L. 280 states Optional P.L. 280 states Indian reservations (U.S. Census Bureau) Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics Overview Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities Duren Banks, Steven W. Perry, and Allina Lee Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 Brian Reaves State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 Steven W. Perry, Ron Malega, and Duren Banks Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 Todd Minton Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System Mark Motivans and Howard Snyder Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 2 June 2011 Bureau of Justice Statistics James P. Lynch Director BJS Website: www.bjs.gov For information contact: BJS Clearinghouse 1-800-732-3277 The Bureau of Justice Statistics is the statistics agency of the U.S. Department of Justice. Duren Banks coordinated the development of this compendium. Contributing authors include Duren Banks, Allina Lee, Ron Malega, Todd Minton, Mark Motivans, Steven W. Perry, Brian Reaves, and Howard Snyder. In addition to the authors, other BJS staff who contributed to verification include Paul Guerino, Tracey Kyckelhahn, and Tracy L. Snell. Morgan Young and Jill Thomas edited the report, Barbara Quinn designed and produced the report, and Jayne Robinson and Tina Dorsey prepared the report for final printing under the supervision of Doris J. James. June 2011, NCJ 234459 3Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 BJS Mandatory P.L. 280 states Optional P.L. 280 states Indian reservations (U.S. Census Bureau) Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics Overview Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities Duren Banks, Steven W. Perry, and Allina Lee Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 Brian Reaves State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 Steven W. Perry, Ron Malega, and Duren Banks Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 Todd Minton Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System Mark Motivans and Howard Snyder 4 June 2011 Content s Overview 7 Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities 9 The Tribal Law and Order Act, 2010 (TLOA; Pub. L. No. 111-211, 124 Stat. 2258, Section 251(b)) requires the Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS) to establish and implement a tribal data collection system and to support tribal participation in national records and information systems. This is the first BJS report on the status of tribal data collection activities as required by the act. It describes BJS’s activities between July 2010 and June 2011 to improve tribal law enforcement reporting to the FBI’s Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) and BJS’s direct collaboration with tribal criminal justice systems to collect data about tribal court systems. It summarizes data published by BJS on jails in Indian country, tribal law enforcement agencies, state prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction in Indian country, tribal youth in the federal justice system, and reporting to the UCR. It describes activities and funding opportunities to improve tribal crime data collection through programs such as the National Criminal History Improvement Program (NCHIP), the National Instant Criminal Background Check System (NICS), Byrne/JAG funding, and UCR training. Table 1.1. Tribes submitting crime data to the Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) Program and receiving Byrne/Justice Assistance Grant (JAG) awards, FY 2008-2010 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10 Table 1.2. Bureau of Justice Statistics planned program activities in response to the Tribal Law and Order Act . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 13 Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 15 Presents data on tribal law enforcement agencies from the 2008 Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies. This report defines the number and locations of tribal law enforcement agencies, service populations, and the number of sworn and nonsworn employees. It describes agency participation in traditional law enforcement (routine patrol, criminal investigation, and dispatching calls for service), public safety functions (emergency management, animal control, and fire services), specialized functions (search and rescue, tactical operations, and underwater recovery), and court-related activities (executing arrest warrants, enforcing protection orders, and serving process). The report details participation in multiagency task forces involving drug and human trafficking, gangs, violent crime, and antiterrorism. It presents data on community outreach efforts, such as school resource officers and community policing officers. Table 2.1. Tribally operated law enforcement agencies, by type of agency and number of full-time sworn personnel, 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 16 Table 2.2. The 25 largest tribally operated law enforcement agencies, by the number of full-time sworn personnel, 2008. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17 Table 2.3. Use of community policing and school resource officers by tribal police departments, 2000 and 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 18 Figure 2.1. Location of tribally operated law enforcement agencies, 2008 . 15 Figure 2.2. Selected law enforcement functions performed by tribal police departments, 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 18 Figure 2.3. Selected court-related functions performed by tribal police departments, 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 18 Figure 2.4. Selected special functions performed by tribal police departments, 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 19 Figure 2.5. Task force participation of tribal police departments, 2008 . . . 19 State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 21 Describes state prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction in Indian country under Public Law 83-280 (P.L. 280). This report examines the activities of prosecutors’ offices in states affected by P.L. 280 through either mandatory or optional jurisdiction. Six states have mandatory jurisdiction under P.L. 280 over crimes in Indian country: Alaska, California, Minnesota (except the Red Lake Reservation), Nebraska, Oregon (except the Warm Springs Reservation), and Wisconsin. The report also examines activities of prosecutors’ offices in the 10 states that have an option to assume jurisdiction over crimes in Indian country within their borders: Arizona, Florida, Idaho, Iowa, Montana, Nevada, North Dakota, South Dakota, Utah, and Washington. Using data from the 2007 National Census of State Court Prosecutors, this report describes the characteristics of state prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction for crimes committed in Indian country, including budgets, staffing, and caseload. It also examines the types of offenses committed in Indian country that were prosecuted in 2007. Table 3.1. Number of tribes participating in the Census of Tribal Justice Agencies in Indian Country, by P.L. 280 status, type of court systems, and state, 2002 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 22 Table 3.2. State prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction for crimes committed in Indian country, by P.L. 280 status, 2007 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 22 Table 3.3. Type of state prosecutors’ offices in Indian country, by P.L. 280 status, 2007. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 25 Table 3.4. Budget, staffing, and caseload of state prosecutors’ offices, by P.L. 280 status, 2007 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 25 Figure 3.1. State prosecutors’ offices reporting jurisdiction in Indian country under P.L. 280, 2007 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 23 Figure 3.2. State prosecutors’ offices reporting prosecution of specific crimes in Indian country, by P.L. 280 status, 2007 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 24 5Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 Contents (continued) Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 27 Presents selected findings from the bulletin Jails in Indian Country, 2009, released in February 2011 (NCJ232223). Data are based on an enumeration of 80 jails, confinement facilities, detention centers, and other facilities operated by tribal authorities or the Bureau of Indian Affairs (BIA) reported to the annual Survey of Jails in Indian Country. The report includes data on the number of adults and juveniles held, type of offense, number of persons confined on the last weekday of each month, average daily population, peak population, and admissions in June 2009. It also summarizes rated capacity, facility crowding, and jail staffing. Table 4.1. Inmates, rated capacity, and percent of capacity occupied in Indian country jails, 2004 and 2007-2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 28 Table 4.2. Jails in Indian country that held the majority of inmates in 2009 compared to 2008, by facility . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 28 Table 4.3. Number of Indian country jails, by percent of rated capacity occupied, June 2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 29 Table 4.4. Admissions and expected length of stay in Indian country jails during June, by facility size, June 2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 30 Table 4.5. Number of inmates confined in Indian country jails, by demographic characteristics, conviction status, and offense, midyear 2000, 2002, 2004, and 2007-2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 31 Table 4.6. Number of persons employed in Indian country jails, by job function, June 30, 2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 32 Figure 4.1. Inmates confined in Indian country jails, at midyear 2000-2004 and 2007-2009. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 27 Figure 4.2. Percent of rated capacity occupied, by type of inmate count, June 2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 29 Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 35 Presents findings on tribal youth processed through the federal criminal justice system between 1999 and 2008. Findings are from a recent study conducted by the Urban Institute under the Bureau of Justice Statistics’ Federal Justice Statistics Program (FJSP). This report describes the number of tribal youth in the federal system and examines how they are handled through the stages of the federal criminal case process, from arrest to confinement. It describes tribal youth demographic characteristics, offenses, and case outcomes, such as referrals for prosecution, dismissal rates, sentencing, and time served. Table 5.1. Reason for matters declined for prosecution with tribal youth suspects, 2005-2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 37 Table 5.2. Federally recognized tribes and enrolled members, 2005. . . . . 38 Table 5.3. Tribal and non-tribal youth admitted to the Federal Bureau of Prisons, by offense type, 1944-2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 41 Figure 5.1. Tribal youth referred to and prosecuted by U.S. attorneys, 2000-2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 35 Figure 5.2. Case-related reasons for declination, 2005-2008 . . . . . . . . . 37 Figure 5.3. Tribal youth admitted to the custody of federal prison authorities, and five federal judicial districts that committed the majority of tribal youth, 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 38 Figure 5.4. Maximum time in federal custody of juveniles adjudicated delinquent . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 39 Figure 5.5. Tribal youth in the Federal Bureau of Prisons, by status, at admission, 2000-2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40 Figure 5.6. Non-tribal youth admitted to the Federal Bureau of Prisons, by status, at admission, 2000-2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40 Figure 5.7. Non-tribal youth admitted to the custody of federal prison authorities, and five federal judicial districts that committed the majority of tribal youth, 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 42 Highlights Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities 9 � The Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS) consulted with tribal leaders through a variety of forums in 2010. � For the first time, the Bureau of Indian Affairs’ (BIA) submissions to the Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) were disaggregated by tribe and reported in Crime in the U.S., 2009. � The number of tribes eligible for Byrne/JAG funding increased from 5 to 22. � In 2008, 140 tribal law enforcement staff received UCR training. � BJS provided competitive funding opportunities for jurisdictions to improve criminal records. � BJS developed a multifaceted data collection system that both established new collections and enhanced current programs. 6 June 2011 Highlights (continued) Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 15 � Tribally operated law enforcement agencies employed nearly 4,600 full-time personnel, including about 3,000 sworn officers. � The largest tribal law enforcement agency, the Navajo Police Department, employed 393 full-time sworn personnel in Arizona, New Mexico, and Utah. � Eleven of the 25 largest tribal law enforcement agencies served jurisdictions covering more than 1,000 square miles. � Overall, tribal police departments cost about $257 per resident to operate during fiscal year 2008. � In addition to law enforcement functions, nearly all tribal police departments performed court-related functions, such as court security and serving process. � More than half of tribal police departments used community policing officers, and more than a third used school resource officers. � About 4 in 5 tribal police departments participated in one or more multiagency task forces. State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 21 � Ninety-three state court prosecutors’ offices in the 16 P.L. 280 states reported jurisdiction for felonies committed in Indian country under P.L. 280. � Seventy-three percent of offices with jurisdiction in Indian country reported prosecuting at least one felony case committed in Indian country. � Most offices in P.L. 280 states prosecuted at least one offense involving drugs (63%), domestic violence (60%), or aggravated assault (58%). � Eighteen offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states with jurisdiction for Indian country prosecuted at least one rape, and 12 offices prosecuted a homicide. � Of state prosecutors’ offices that reported jurisdiction for felony cases in Indian country under P.L. 280, 70% served judicial districts with populations of less than 100,000 residents. � Offices with jurisdiction for felony crimes committed in Indian country had an average operating budget of $5.2 million in 2007. Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 27 � The number of inmates confined in Indian country jails increased by 1.9% between midyear 2008 and 2009, reaching 2,176 inmates. � Between June 2008 and June 2009, the average daily jail population in Indian country increased by 12%, and the percentage of occupied bed space increased from 64.2% to 73.5%. � Eleven jails (14% of all facilities) held 51% of inmates confined at midyear 2009. � During June 2009, the number of inmates admitted to Indian country jails (11,357) was about 5 times the size of the average daily population (2,124). � The expected average length of stay increased by a half day from 5.1 days during June 2008 to 5.6 days during June 2009. � Indian country jail authorities reported no deaths in custody between July 1, 2008, and June 30, 2009, down from 4 reported deaths during the 12-month period ending June 30, 2008. � Attempted suicides by inmates declined from 78 in 2008 to 56 in 2009. � Indian country jails held fewer inmates for domestic violence at midyear 2009 (252), continuing the downward trend in the number held for this offense since 2007 (362). � The percentage of certified correctional officers working in Indian country jails increased steadily, from 63% at midyear 2007 to 79% at midyear 2009. Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 35 � In 2008, relatively few juveniles were referred to federal prosecutors (315 out of 178,570 suspects) or admitted to federal prison jurisdiction (156 out 71,663 offenders). � Tribal youth (70) comprised nearly half of juveniles (152) handled by the federal courts in 2008. � Federal judicial districts of Arizona, Montana, South Dakota, New Mexico, and North Dakota accounted for 94% of tribal youth investigated, 92% of those prosecuted, and 88% of those admitted to federal prison jurisdiction in 2008. � In 2008, about 72% of tribal youth were investigated for violent offenses, including sexual abuse (35%), assault (20%), and murder (17%). � About 40% of matters involving tribal youth were declined by federal prosecutors in 2008. � A greater share of cases involving tribal youth in U.S. district courts were terminated by conviction (91%) than by dismissal (9%). � From 1994 to 2008, the lowest number of tribal (72) and non-tribal youth (84) admitted to the jurisdiction of federal prison authorities occurred in 2008. � Admissions to federal prison jurisdiction among tribal youth declined 10% per year from 1999 to 2008, while non-tribal youth admissions declined 12% per year. � In 2008, tribal youth served an average of 26 months under federal jurisdiction, which was more than double the tribal justice system maximum sentence of 12 months. 7Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 Overview The Tribal Law and Order Act (TLOA), enacted July 29, 2010, requires the Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS) to (1) establish and implement a tribal data collection system and (2) support tribal participation in national records and information systems (P.L. 111-211, 124 Stat. 2258, § 251(b)). The act further requires the director of BJS to consult with Indian tribes to establish and implement this data collection system. The BJS director is required to report to Congress within one year of enactment, and annually thereafter, the data collected and analyzed in accordance with the act. This report describes activities in support of BJS’s tribal crime data collection system and summarizes findings published from that system between July 2010 and June 2011. Multifaceted data collection system Criminal jurisdiction in Indian country—federally recognized reservations, tribal communities, and identified trust lands—varies by the type of crime committed, whether the offender or victim was a tribal member, and the state in which the offense occurred. Due to the sovereign status of federally recognized tribes in the United States, crimes committed in Indian country are often subject to concurrent jurisdiction between multiple criminal justice agencies. Public Law 83-280 (P.L. 280) gave select states legal jurisdiction over tribal members to prosecute crimes that occur on the reservation under existing state laws. These mandatory P.L. 280 states include California, Minnesota (except the Red Lake Reservation), Nebraska, Oregon (except the Warm Springs Reservation), Wisconsin, and Alaska. P.L. 280 permitted other states to acquire jurisdiction over crimes committed in Indian country at their option. These optional P.L. 280 states assume jurisdiction, either in whole or in part, over Indian country within their boundaries, and include Arizona, Florida, Idaho, Iowa, Montana, Nevada, North Dakota, South Dakota, Utah, and Washington. In the remaining states, where P.L. 280 does not apply, federal and tribal governments maintain concurrent jurisdiction for major crimes committed in Indian country (as defined in the Major Crimes Act and subsequent amendments (18 U.S.C. § 1153)). Tribal governments have jurisdiction for all other crimes committed in Indian country that involve both an Indian offender and Indian victim. States retain jurisdiction for non-Indian crimes committed in Indian country—those in which neither the offender nor the victim is a tribal member. Due in part to these jurisdictional complexities, existing tribal data systems are often limited in scope and applicable only to certain jurisdictions or states. An effective tribal data collection system will include data from federal, state, local, and tribal agencies. The information maintained in this system should further be considered in light of the concurrent jurisdictional roles multiple agencies maintain in Indian country. Recent findings from the tribal data collection system 178 tribal law enforcement agencies operated in 2008 In September 2008, American Indian tribes operated 178 law enforcement agencies. These 178 agencies employed at least one full-time sworn officer with general arrest powers or the equivalent in part-time officers. The total includes 157 general purpose tribal police departments and 21 special jurisdiction agencies tasked with enforcing natural resources laws that pertain primarily to hunting and fishing on tribal lands. Tribes operated law enforcement agencies in 28 states and employed about 3,000 full-time sworn personnel. Eleven of the 25 largest tribal law enforcement agencies served jurisdictions of more than 1,000 square miles. (See Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008, page 15, for more information.) 83 tribal law enforcement agencies provided data through the Bureau of Indian Affairs (BIA) that met the FBI’s guidelines for publication Offenses known to tribal law enforcement agencies were reported by tribal agencies in the FBI’s Crime in the United States, 2009. Eighty-three tribal law enforcement agencies met FBI guidelines for data publication in the report.* Nearly 3,800 violent crimes and approximately 11,400 property crimes were known to *Crimes known to tribal law enforcement agencies are submitted to the UCR through the BIA. UCR data must be submitted by local law enforcement with a valid reporting number, and be complete for all 12 months of the year. Data submitted to the UCR must also meet FBI data quality guidelines for publication in Crime in the U.S. 8 June 2011 these selected tribal law enforcement agencies in 2009. (See the FBI’s Crime in the United States, 2009, http:// www2.fbi.gov/ucr/cius2009/data/ table_11.html, for more information.) 93 state prosecutors’ offices in P.L. 280 states reported jurisdiction for felonies committed in Indian country In 2007, 93 state court prosecutors’ offices reported jurisdiction under P.L. 280 for felonies committed in Indian country. Seventy-three percent of these offices reported prosecuting at least one felony case that arose from Indian country in 2007, including at least one offense that involved drugs (63%), domestic violence (60%), or aggravated assault (58%). Most state prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction under P.L. 280 served districts with 100,000 or fewer residents. (See State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007, page 21, for more information.) Jails in Indian country housed 2,176 inmates in 2009 The number of inmates confined in Indian country jails increased by 1.9% between midyear 2008 and midyear 2009, from 2,135 to 2,176 inmates. Over the 12 months ending June 2009, the average daily jail population in Indian country increased by 12%, and the percentage of occupied bed space increased from 64.2% to 73.5%. (See Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009, page 27, for more information.) Most tribal youth in the federal system were referred for violent offenses Between 1999 and 2008, 65% of tribal youth in criminal matters received by federal prosecutors were referred for a violent offense. Sexual abuse was the most common violent offense, followed by assault and murder. In 2008, federal prosecutors received 129 tribal youth suspects in matters opened out of 178,570 total matters investigated. Tribal youth admitted to the legal custody of federal prison authorities were mostly male (90%) and tended to be older teens; more than two-thirds were between the ages 16 and 17. (See Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System, page 35, for more information.) 9Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities, 2011 The Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS), in collaboration with other federal agencies and American Indian tribes, conducted several activities to develop the tribal data collection system as of June 2011. The data collection system establishes both new data collections and enhances current programs to carry out the requirements of the Tribal Law and Order Act (TLOA), 2010. BJS focused on improving tribal law enforcement reporting to the FBI’s Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) and developed direct data collection from tribal criminal justice systems, such as collecting information about the nature and operation of tribal court systems. Efforts also include activities and funding opportunities to improve tribal crime data collection through programs such as the National Criminal History Improvement Program (NCHIP), the National Instant Criminal Background Check System (NICS), Byrne/JAG funding, and UCR training. Activities to Support Tribal Crime Data Collection Systems, July 2010 through June 2011 Tribal consultations conducted in 2010 BJS consulted with tribal leaders through a variety of forums in 2010. BJS developed and distributed an initial plan that responded to the TLOA sections that directly referenced tribal crime data collection. This plan was presented to several stakeholder groups to invite feedback and input, including— � Interdepartmental Tribal Justice Safety and Wellness Consultation, Session 12 (December 2010, Palm Springs, CA) � Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) trainings for tribal law enforcement (2010) agencies � National Congress of American Indians, 2011 Executive Council Winter Meeting (March 2011, Washington, DC). For the first time, the Bureau of Indian Affairs’ (BIA) submissions to UCR were disaggregated by tribe and reported in the FBI’s Crime in the U.S., 2009 Working with the Office of Justice Services in the BIA, and the Office of Tribal Justice and the FBI in the Department of Justice (DOJ), BJS developed a process to support tribal access to, and input in, regional and national criminal justice databases, including the National Crime Information Center (NCIC) and the Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR). As a result of this process, data provided to the FBI from the BIA were able to be disaggregated by tribe. Offenses known to tribal law enforcement agencies were reported by tribal agencies in the FBI’s Crime in the United States, 2009. Eighty- three tribal law enforcement agencies met FBI guidelines for data to be published in the report. Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities, 2011 Duren Banks, Ph.D., and Steven W. Perry, BJS Statisticians Allina Lee, BJS Policy Analyst U.S. Department of Justice Office of Justice Programs Bureau of Justice Statistics June 2011, NCJ 234518 Highlights � The Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS) consulted with tribal leaders through a variety of forums in 2010. � For the first time, the Bureau of Indian Affairs’ (BIA) submissions to the Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) were disaggregated by tribe and reported in Crime in the U.S., 2009. � The number of tribes eligible for Byrne/JAG funding increased from 5 in 2008 to 22 in 2010. � In 2010, 140 tribal law enforcement staff received UCR training. � BJS provided competitive funding opportunities for jurisdictions to improve criminal records in fiscal year 2011. � BJS developed a multifaceted data collection system that both established new collections and enhanced current programs. 10 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 The number of tribes eligible for Byrne/ JAG funding increased from 5 in fiscal year 2008 to 22 in fiscal year 2010 Collaborative efforts between the departments of Justice and Interior have increased the number of tribes reporting monthly crime data to the UCR, thereby increasing the number of tribes eligible to receive Byrne/JAG awards. Byrne/JAG funds can be used to support a range of activities in seven broad program areas, including law enforcement; prosecution and courts; crime prevention and education; corrections; drug treatment and enforcement; program planning, evaluation, and technology improvement; and crime victim and witness programs. Most American Indian tribes had been ineligible to receive Byrne/JAG funds because of gaps in Indian country crime statistics and traditional methods for reporting data. Prior to 2009, BIA provided an aggregate number of crimes known to tribal law enforcement to the UCR. Since these data could not be disaggregated by tribe, tribal law enforcement agencies that did not submit information directly to the UCR were not eligible for Byrne/JAG awards. In FY 2008, 25 tribes submitted crime data directly to the FBI, with 5 of the tribes eligible to receive Byrne/JAG awards totaling $150,000. In FY 2010, the number of tribes that submitted crime data increased to 144 following collaborative efforts between agencies in the departments of Justice and Interior, with 22 tribes eligible for Byrne/JAG awards totaling $709,000 (table 1.1). More than 140 tribal law enforcement staff received UCR training Through Recovery Act funds, BJS developed and implemented the Tribal Crime Data project to further support the reporting of tribal crime to the UCR, and thereby establish eligibility for Byrne/ JAG funds. The project is also part of BJS’s larger effort to collect more reliable information on American Indians in the criminal justice system and crimes committed in Indian country. Through the Tribal Crime Data project, BJS conducted three training sessions in 2010, with more than 140 tribal members, on the use of the UCR systems. In 2011 the project provided training and technical assistance to tribes that did not meet FBI data quality guidelines or had not previously submitted complete crime data to BIA. Table 1.1 Tribes submitting crime data to the Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) and receiving Justice Assistance Grant (JAG) awards, FY 2008–2010 Number of tribes— Fiscal Year Reporting to UCR Eligible for JAG award Eligible award amount 2008 25 5 $150,000 2009 106 20 559,000 2010 144 22 709,000 BJS, acting jointly with the Office of Justice Services, BIA (DOI), and the FBI (DOJ), will work with tribes and tribal law enforcement to establish and implement tribal data collection systems (P.L. 111-211 § 251(b)). 11Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities, 2011 Funding for improving criminal records To improve criminal records, BJS provided outreach to agencies in tribal jurisdictions through two competitive funding opportunities: � National Criminal History Improvement Program (NCHIP) solicitation, 2011 � National Instant Criminal Background Check System (NICS) Act Record Improvement Program (NARIP) solicitation, 2011. The TLOA made federally recognized tribes eligible for awards under BJS’s NCHIP. State and tribal entities apply for NCHIP funds to enhance the crime fighting and criminal justice capabilities of governments by improving the accuracy, utility, and interstate accessibility of criminal history records. Jurisdictions also apply for NCHIP funds to enhance records of protective orders that involve domestic violence and stalking, sex offender records, automated identification systems, and other state systems that support national records systems and their use for criminal history background checks. BJS released the FY 2011 NCHIP solicitation on January 13, 2011, and collaborated with other OJP components to disseminate information about the NCHIP funding announcement as broadly as possible. Tribal contacts were alerted via email to the funding opportunity, and the solicitation was posted to the BJS and DOJ Tribal Safety and Justice websites. Information about the NCHIP funding opportunity was also presented during several meetings and a consultation in the fall and winter of 2010. Additionally, BJS developed an addendum to the solicitation that identified priority funding areas and eligibility requirements for tribal applicants. The addendum outlined key tribal priority areas activities related to— � information technology systems to capture and transmit tribal issued domestic violence and stalking records to the FBI NCIC Protection Order File � automation and transmission of existing qualifying domestic violence and stalking records to the FBI NCIC Protection Order File. The NARIP implements the provisions of the NICS Improvement Amendments Act of 2007, enacted in the wake of the shooting tragedy at Virginia Tech and includes tribes as eligible entities. The NARIP funds provide assistance to eligible states and tribes to improve the completeness, automation, and transmittal of records needed by the NICS to identify persons prohibited from receiving or possessing a firearm. These records include prohibited mental health adjudications and commitments, felony convictions, felony indictments, fugitives from justice, drug arrests and convictions, domestic violence protection orders, and misdemeanor crimes of domestic violence. BJS will award FY 2011 NARIP funds to support efforts to improve the records used by NICS, by providing assistance to states and tribes to improve the completeness, automation, and transmittal of records to state and federal systems. BJS released the FY 2011 NARIP solicitation on March 15, 2011. The same process used to disseminate information about the NCHIP funding opportunity was followed to alert tribes to the NARIP solicitation. Subject to the availability of appropriated funds and any modifications or additional requirements that may be imposed by law, BJS plans to competitively award NCHIP and NARIP funds in FY 2011. Eligible applications will be evaluated and scored by peer reviewers, and funding will be made based on the selection criteria outlined in the solicitations. BJS is authorized to provide for improvements in the accuracy, quality, timeliness, immediate accessibility, and integration of state and tribal criminal history and related records (P.L. 111-211 § 251(b)(1)(H)). 12 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 BJS established new collections and enhanced current programs In addition to collaborating with other federal agencies to improve tribal law enforcement reporting to the UCR, BJS developed a plan to collect information about tribal criminal justice systems. This multipronged approach both established new collections and enhanced current programs that serve the purposes of the TLOA. Through its ongoing statistical projects, BJS provided information on (1) suspects and defendants processed in the federal criminal justice system, including federal prosecutions of crimes committed in Indian country, (2) the incidence of crimes known to law enforcement that occur on tribal reservations or were reported by Indian country law enforcement authorities, (3) the characteristics of tribal law enforcement agencies, and (4) the characteristics of jails in Indian country. BJS plans to begin collecting information about the nature and operation of tribal court systems in 2012 (table 1.2). Survey of Tribal Court Systems BJS developed the Survey of Tribal Court Systems to build on BJS’s previous Census of Tribal Justice Agencies (See Census of Tribal Justice Agencies in Indian Country, 2002, BJS Web, December 2005). The survey will gather administrative and operational information from tribal courts, prosecutors’ offices, and indigent defense providers operating in the estimated 190 federally recognized tribal justice systems in the U.S. Subject to the availability of appropriated funds and any modifications or additional requirements that may be imposed by law, BJS plans to award the Survey of Tribal Court Systems in FY 2011. BJS will work with the awardee and collaborating organizations to develop the data collection instrument and methodology. The instrument will include, at a minimum, measures of tribal court organization, court caseload, characteristics of prosecutors in tribal courts, and systems to provide indigent defense in tribal courts. Based on the results of the initial data collection, BJS will devise a strategy for conducting a regular data collection program among Indian country court systems. Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies The Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies provides data on staffing, functions, and expenditures. Data collected include the number of sworn and civilian personnel by state and type of agency, and functions performed by each agency. BJS analyzed and published findings from data collected in 2008, from the Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies program, including 178 tribal law enforcement agencies. Survey of Jails in Indian Country The Survey of Jails in Indian Country data describe jails, confinement facilities, detention centers, and other facilities operated by tribal authorities or BIA. The annual report from the Survey of Jails in Indian Country includes data on the number of adults and juveniles held, type of offense, number of persons confined on the last weekday of each month, average daily population, peak population, and admissions at midyear. It also summarizes rated capacity, facility crowding, and jail staffing. The most recent report that describes findings from the 2009 survey was released in February 2011. National Census of State Court Prosecutors In 2007 BJS conducted the National Census of State Prosecutors, which was the second complete enumeration of all chief prosecutors who tried felony cases in state courts of general jurisdiction. The census collected information about whether district The director of BJS will establish and implement a tribal data collection system (P.L. 111-211 § 251(b)). 13Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities, 2011 Table 1.2 Bureau of Justice Statistics Planned Program Activities in Response to the Tribal Law and Order Act Program Objective Timeline Collaboration with DOJ Components and BIA To increase the number of tribes eligible to receive Edward Byrne Memorial Justice Assistance Grant (JAG) Program funds, ensure tribal access to regional and national databases, and develop comprehensive tribal crime data systems. Ongoing. BJS Recovery Act Program To support tribes to more accurately and consistently report tribal crime data to the BIA and/or the FBI through technical assistance, training, and information sharing. Crimes known to some tribal law enforcement agencies published in Crime in the United States, 2009 and annually thereafter. Grants to Support Tribal Participation in Regional and National Databases To continue to include federally-recognized tribes as eligible entities for the National Instant Criminal Background Check System (NICS) Act Record Improvement Program and add federally- recognized tribes as eligible entities to the National Criminal History Improvement Program (NCHIP) grant awards. Tribes are eligible for awards as of FY 2009 (NICS) and FY 2011 (NCHIP). Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies To collect data from all state, local, and tribal law enforcement agencies on staffing, expenditures and functions. BJS will continue to implement strategies designed to accurately represent the work of tribal law enforcement agencies. Periodically since 1992. Latest report: 2004 census 2008 census report in 2011. Survey of Tribal Court Systems To gather administrative and operational information from tribal courts, prosecutors’ offices, and indigent defense providers. Award: August 2011. Design and Data Collection: 2011-2012. Analysis and Reporting: Early 2013. Survey of Jails in Indian Country The survey is an annual enumeration of jails, confinement facilities, detention centers, and other facilities operated by tribal authorities or the BIA. Data are collected intermittently via an addendum to the core survey on the physical conditions and operations of Indian country facilities. The addendum requests information on inmate medical services, mental health services, suicide prevention procedures, substance dependency programs, domestic violence counseling, sex offender treatment, education programs, and inmate work assignments. Annually since 1998. Latest report: 2009 survey 2010 survey report expected in 2011. Federal Justice Statistics Program To compile comprehensive information describing suspects and defendants processed in the federal criminal justice system. Ongoing since 1998. Annual data through 2009 available on the BJS website. BJS Native American Crime Information Website To provide users with easy-to-access and current information from existing and new data collection programs Design and populate website: 2010-2011. Public release: Late 2011. 14 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 attorney offices have jurisdiction for prosecuting felony cases occurring in Indian country under P.L. 280, and what types of crimes the office prosecuted. The findings from this data collection are in State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country on page 21. Federal Justice Statistics Program The Federal Justice Statistics Program (FJSP) provides comprehensive and detailed information about the federal justice system’s processing of criminal cases. The FJSP provides annual data on workload, activities, and outcomes associated with federal criminal cases. Information is acquired on all aspects of processing in the federal justice system, including arrests, prosecution decisions, referrals to magistrates, court dispositions, sentencing outcomes, sentence length, and time served. The FJSP receives the source data from the U.S. Marshals Service, Drug Enforcement Administration, Executive Office of U.S. Attorneys, Administrative Office of the U.S. Courts, U.S. Sentencing Commission, and the Federal Bureau of Prisons. BJS is currently developing research projects that will examine American Indian defendants who are processed in the federal justice system. Findings from the first of these projects, describing characteristics of American Indian youth who are processed in the federal criminal justice system, are in the Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System on page 35. References Crime in the United States, 2009, U.S. Department of Justice, Federal Bureau of Investigation, September 2010. Jails in Indian Country, 2009, NCJ 232223, BJS Web, February 2011. State Prosecutors Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007, NCJ 234241, BJS Web, June 2011. Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008. NCJ 234217, BJS Web, June 2011. Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System, NCJ 234218, BJS Web, June 2011. Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 15 Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 Brian A. Reaves, Ph.D., BJS Statistician In September 2008, American Indian tribes operated 178 law enforcement agencies that employed at least one full-time sworn officer with general arrest powers or the equivalent in part-time officers. The total includes 157 general purpose tribal police departments and 21 special jurisdiction agencies tasked with enforcing natural resources laws that pertain primarily to hunting and fishing on tribal lands. Collectively, tribes operated law enforcement agencies in 28 states. Washington (24), Arizona (22), Oklahoma (19), and New Mexico (17) had the largest numbers of tribal law enforcement agencies (figure 2.1). These findings are based on the 2008 Bureau of Justice Statistics’ (BJS) Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies. In addition to tribally operated agencies, the Department of the Interior’s (DOI) Bureau of Indian Affairs (BIA) operated 42 agencies that provided law enforcement Highlights � Tribally operated law enforcement agencies employed nearly 4,600 full-time personnel, including about 3,000 sworn officers. � The largest tribal law enforcement agency, the Navajo Police Department, employed 393 full-time sworn personnel in Arizona, New Mexico, and Utah. � Eleven of the 25 largest tribal law enforcement agencies served jurisdictions covering more than 1,000 square miles. � Overall, tribal police departments cost about $257 per resident to operate during FY 2008. � In addition to law enforcement functions, nearly all tribal police departments performed court-related functions, such as court security and serving process. � More than half of tribal police departments used community policing officers, and more than a third used school resource officers. � About 4 in 5 tribal police departments participated in one or more multiagency task forces. U.S. Department of Justice Office of Justice Programs Bureau of Justice Statistics June 2011 NCJ 234217 No tribally operated LE agencies Under 5 agencies 5-9 agencies 10 or more agencies Figure 2.1 Location of tribally operated law enforcement agencies, 2008 Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics, Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies, 2008 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201116 services in Indian country. Nationwide, BIA employed 277 full-time sworn personnel in 2008. Along with direct oversight of its own programs, BIA also provided technical assistance and some oversight to tribally operated agencies. On the more than 300 federal Indian reservation areas in the U.S., police officers may be tribal, federal, state, county, or municipal employees. Some areas may be served by more than one type of officer. Commonly, tribal police department funding, administration, and employees are based on the Indian Self-Determination and Education Assistance Act of 1975, (Public Law 93-638 or P.L. 638). This law allowed tribes to assume responsibility for many programs previously administered by the federal government, including law enforcement. P.L. 638 agencies operate with tribal employees under contract and with financial assistance from the BIA. Tribally operated agencies can also function under a self-governance compact with the BIA. This arrangement provides block grant payments, allowing for more tribal control than the line item funding of P.L. 638 contracts. Full tribal control over law enforcement services exists where such services are entirely funded by the tribal government. Jurisdiction over offenses in Indian country may lie with federal, state, or tribal agencies, depending on the offense, offender, victim, and offense location. Most tribes have cross- deputization agreements, often with neighboring nontribal agencies. These agreements allow law enforcement personnel from state, local, and tribal entities to cross jurisdictions in criminal cases, and can be used to enhance law enforcement capabilities in areas where state and tribal lands are contiguous and intermingled. In some instances, the number of agreements is large. For example, the Cherokee Nation Marshal Service is cross-deputized with 50 municipal, county, state, and federal agencies. Tribal police departments employed 2.3 full-time officers per 1,000 residents In September 2008, the 178 operating tribal law enforcement agencies employed more than 4,500 full- time personnel, including about 3,000 sworn officers (table 2.1). The 157 general purpose tribal police departments employed 4,294 full-time personnel, including 2,835 sworn officers and 1,459 civilian personnel. These agencies employed an additional 129 part-time personnel, including 80 sworn officers (not shown in table). The 21 natural resources agencies employed 271 full-time personnel, including 164 sworn officers and 107 civilian employees. These natural resources agencies also employed 11 part-time personnel, including 7 sworn officers (not shown in table). General purpose tribal police departments had a combined service population of about 1.2 million residents.* This corresponds to about 2.3 full-time sworn officers per 1,000 residents, which was the national average for all local police departments as of 2007. (See Local Police Departments, 2007, BJS Web, December 2010.) Collectively, tribal police departments cost $257 per resident to operate for 2008 (not shown in table). In 2007 the national average for all local police departments was $260 per resident. *Based on the American Indian service population counts published in BIA’s American Indian Population and Labor Force Report, 2005. The service population is the total number of enrolled tribal members and members from other tribes who live on or near the reservation and are eligible to use the BIA- funded tribal services. The service population excludes any non-Indian residents served by a tribally operated law enforcement agency and other persons using roads, stores, casinos, and other public places on tribal land. Table 2.1 Tribally operated law enforcement agencies, by type of agency and number of full-time sworn personnel, 2008 Type of agency and number of full-time sworn personnel Number of agencies Number of full-time employees Total Sworn Civilian All agencies 178 4,565 2,999 1,566 General purpose police departments Total 157 4,294 2,835 1,459 50 or more 6 1,397 871 526 25-49 19 955 607 348 10-24 61 1,380 955 425 5-9 47 479 332 147 Under 5 24 83 70 13 Natural resources agencies Total 21 271 164 107 10-24 8 154 107 47 5-9 4 38 29 9 Under 5 9 79 28 51 Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 17 11 of the 25 largest tribal law enforcement agencies served jurisdictions of more than 1,000 square miles The 25 largest tribally operated agencies employed at least 25 full- time sworn personnel. The largest agency, the Navajo Police Department, employed 393 full-time officers to serve tribal lands in Arizona, New Mexico, and Utah (table 2.2). The next largest were the Seminole Police Department (Florida) with 144 officers, and the Salt River Police Department (Arizona) with 125 officers. The BIA service population for the 25 largest agencies ranged from less than 1,000 to about 200,000 residents. Although not all reservations are open to the public, many tribal law enforcement agencies deal with a significant number of daily visitors in addition to the resident population. The natural resources of tribal lands attract visitors, as do conference facilities and casinos. All of the 25 largest agencies had at least one casino operating within their jurisdictional area. The amount of land area served by a tribal law enforcement agency can be quite large. For example, the Navajo Police Department has jurisdiction over about 22,000 square miles, a larger land area than any county in the continental United States. Ten other agencies among the 25 largest had jurisdictional areas exceeding 1,000 square miles, a larger land area than any city in the continental United States. Table 2.2 The 25 largest tribally operated law enforcement agencies, by the number of full-time sworn personnel, 2008 Name and location of agency Number of full-time sworn personnel BIA service population, 2005 Full-time sworn personnel per 1,000 residents Reservation land area (square miles) Full-time sworn personnel per 25 square miles Navajo Police Department (AZ, NM, UT) 393 192,067 2.0 22,174 0.4 Seminole Police Department (FL) 144 3,165 45.5 141 25.5 Salt River Police Department (AZ) 125 7,313 17.1 81 38.6 Gila River Indian Community Police Department (AZ) 93 14,966 6.2 584 4.0 Tohono O’odham Police Department (AZ) 66 26,673 2.5 4,453 0.4 Choctaw Police Department (MS) 50 8,313 6.0 25 50.0 Oglala Sioux Tribe Department of Public Safety (SD) 49 43,146 1.1 3,159 0.4 Cherokee Indian Police Department (NC) 45 13,562 3.3 83 13.6 Muscogee (Creek) Nation Lighthorse Tribal Police (OK) 39 55,817 0.7 4,648 0.2 Miccosukee Police Department (FL) 36 589 61.1 128 7.0 Poarch Creek Tribal Police Department (AL) 33 1,567 21.1 0.4 -- Cherokee Nation Marshal Service (OK) 32 197,684 0.2 6,702 0.1 Choctaw Nation Tribal Police Department (OK) 32 99,371 0.3 10,613 0.1 Colville Tribal Police Department (WA) 32 5,052 6.3 2,117 0.4 Saginaw Chippewa Tribal Police Department (MI) 30 1,799 16.7 218 3.4 Tulalip Tribal Police Services (WA) 30 2,869 10.5 35 21.4 Warm Springs Tribal Police Department (OR) 30 4,079 7.4 1,011 0.7 White Mountain Apache Police Department (AZ) 30 12,213 2.5 2,628 0.3 Isleta Police Department (NM) 29 3,980 7.3 331 2.2 Yakama Nation Tribal Police Department (WA) 28 16,815 1.7 2,153 0.3 Pascua Yaqui Tribal Police Department (AZ) 27 14,787 1.8 2 -- Puyallup Tribal Police Department (WA) 27 24,016 1.1 29 23.3 Rosebud Sioux Tribal Police Department (SD) 27 22,293 1.2 1,388 0.5 Red Lake Tribal Police Department (MN) 26 10,338 2.5 880 0.7 Oneida Indian Nation Police (NY) 25 650 38.5 0.1 -- Note: Land area data are from the U.S. Census Bureau, and include reservation land only. --Reservation land area is less than 25 square miles. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201118 Tribal law enforcement agencies were responsible for a broad range of services and functions during 2008 Nearly all general purpose tribal police departments were responsible for traditional law enforcement functions, such as routine patrol (100%), responding to citizen requests for service (100%), special events and crowd control (98%), criminal investigation (96%), and traffic enforcement (96%) (figure 2.2). About 4 in 5 departments were responsible for parking enforcement (80%), and about 2 in 3 departments dispatched calls for service (66%). About 3 in 5 general purpose tribal police departments had full-time community policing officers A majority of tribal police departments used a community policing approach in their efforts to prevent crime and maintain partnerships with the communities they serve. About three-fifths (59%) of departments had full-time sworn personnel serving as community policing officers (table 2.3). As of September 2008, about 500 tribal police officers were designated as community policing officers. In 2000, 73% of tribal agencies reported using community policing officers, with about 700 designated as such. For more than a third (36%) of tribal police departments, community policing efforts extended into the schools, with 82 full-time sworn personnel assigned as school resource officers. Although the percentage of departments using school resource officers in 2008 was about the same as in 2000 (37%), the total number of officers was about half of 2000 levels. Nearly all tribal police departments performed a variety of court-related functions In addition to law enforcement duties, nearly all tribal police departments were responsible for a variety of court-related functions (figure 2.3). The most common functions were executing arrest warrants (95%), enforcing protection orders (92%), serving process (89%), apprehending fugitives (88%), and providing court security (75%). Table 2.3 Use of community policing and school resource officers by tribal police departments, 2000 and 2008 2000 2008 Community policing officers Percent of agencies using 73% 59% Number of officers 714 503 School resource officers Percent of agencies using 37% 36% Number of officers 162 82 0 20 40 60 80 100 Percent of agencies Dispatching calls Parking enforcement Accident investigation Crime investigation Tra�c law enforcement Special events/crowd control Responding to calls for service Routine patrol Type of function Figure 2.2 Selected law enforcement functions performed by tribal police departments, 2008 Figure 2.3 Selected court-related functions performed by tribal police departments, 2008 0 20 40 60 80 100 Percent of agencies Type of function Enforcing child support orders Serving eviction notices Inmate transport Court security Apprehension of fugitives Serving process Enforcing protection orders Executing arrest warrants Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 19 Nearly half of tribal police departments were responsible for search and rescue operations Nearly 9 in 10 tribal police departments performed one or more special public safety functions, the most common being emergency management (65%) and animal control (64%) (figure 2.4). About a third (31%) provided emergency medical services. Nearly a fifth provided fire services (19%) and school crossing services (18%). More than half (58%) of tribal police departments performed at least one specialized function, such as search and rescue (43%), tactical operations (26%), or underwater recovery (10%). About 1 in 6 agencies operated at least one jail (17%), and about 1 in 10 agencies operated an overnight lockup facility separate from a jail (10%). (For more information, see Jails in Indian County, 2009, BJS Web, February 2011.) The 21 special jurisdiction agencies, whose primary focus was the enforcement of natural resources laws, performed a variety of functions as well. In addition to providing patrol and response services, a majority of these agencies performed the following functions: criminal investigation (82%), search and rescue (71%), apprehension of fugitives (59%), animal control (59%), traffic enforcement (59%), and dispatching calls for service (53%) (not shown in figure). About two-thirds of general purpose tribal police departments participated in a multiagency drug task force About 4 in 5 (78%) tribal police departments partnered with federal, state, and local agencies in multiagency task forces to combat crime problems in Indian country during 2008. These task forces allow participating agencies to share in pooled resources, information, and expertise across jurisdictional boundaries. Tribal police departments were most likely to participate in task forces formed to combat drug trafficking (66% of agencies) (figure 2.5). About 2 in 5 (41%) departments participated in multiagency gang task forces, and about a third (32%) participated in violent crime task forces. Smaller percentages of tribal police departments participated in anti- terrorism (17%) or human trafficking (9%) task forces. 0 20 40 60 80 Percent of agencies Jail operation School crossing services Fire services Tactical operations (SWAT) Emergency medical services Search and rescue Animal control Emergency management Type of function Figure 2.4 Selected special functions performed by tribal police departments, 2008 0 20 40 60 80 Percent of agencies Human tra�cking Anti- terrorism Violent crime GangsDrug tra�cking One or more types Type of function Figure 2.5 Task force participation of tribal police departments, 2008 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201120 Methodology The Bureau of Justice Statistics’ (BJS) Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies (CSLLEA) is conducted every 4 years to provide a complete enumeration of agencies and their employees. Employment data are reported for sworn and nonsworn personnel and, within these categories, by full-time or part- time status. Agencies also complete a checklist of functions they regularly perform, or for which they have primary responsibility. The CSLLEA provides national data on the number of state and local law enforcement agencies and employees for general purpose local police departments (including tribal agencies), sheriffs’ offices, the primary state law enforcement agencies, and special jurisdiction (e.g., natural resources) agencies. It also serves as the sampling frame for BJS surveys of law enforcement agencies. The 2008 CSLLEA form was mailed to approximately 20,000 agencies that were determined to potentially be operating on the reference date of September 30, 2008. This master list was created by compiling information from the following sources: � the 2004 CSLLEA � lists provided by Peace Officer Standards and Training offices, and other state agencies � an FBI list of agencies requesting new identifiers since the 2004 CSLLEA. Responding agencies were screened for eligibility and were excluded if any of the following conditions existed on the CSLLEA reference date of September 30, 2008: � The agency employed only part-time officers, and the total combined hours worked for these officers averaged less than 35 hours per week. � The agency contracted or outsourced to another agency for performance of all services. � The agency was closed, a duplicate listing, or otherwise an invalid entry on the master list. � The agency did not employ personnel with general arrest powers. � The agency did not operate with funds from a state, local, special district, or tribal government. � All sworn officers volunteered their time on an unpaid basis. Data on number and type of personnel were obtained from all eligible tribal agencies. For general purpose tribal police departments, the item response rates were as follows: community policing and school resource officers, 100%; agency functions, 99%; task force participation, 99%; and operating budget, 87%. References American Indians and Crime, NCJ 173386, BJS Web, February 1999. American Indian Population and Labor Force Report, 2005, U.S. Department of the Interior, Bureau of Indian Affairs, Office of Indian Services. Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies, 2008, NCJ 233982, BJS Web, June 2011. Census of Tribal Justice Agencies in Indian Country, 2002, NCJ 205332, BJS Web, December 2005. Indian Country Law Enforcement Review, U.S. Department of Justice, December 1999. Jails in Indian Country, 2009, NCJ 232223, BJS Web, February 2011. Local Police Departments, 2007, NCJ 231174, BJS Web, December 2010. Policing on American Indian Reservations, U.S. Department of Justice, National Institute of Justice, NCJ 186185, September 2001. Tribal Law Enforcement, 2000, NCJ 197936, BJS Web, January 2003. State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 21 State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 Steven W. Perry, Ron Malega, Ph.D., and Duren Banks, Ph.D., BJS Statisticians In 2007, 93 state court prosecutors’ offices reported jurisdiction under Public Law 83-280 (P.L. 280) for felonies committed in Indian country. Seventy-three percent of these offices prosecuted at least one felony case that arose from Indian country in 2007, including at least one offense that involved drugs (63%), domestic violence (60%), or aggravated assault (58%). This report presents selected findings from the Bureau of Justice Statistics’s (BJS) 2007 National Census of State Prosecutors. Criminal jurisdiction in Indian country is divided among federal, state, and tribal governments. Jurisdiction in a specific incident depends on the nature of the offense, whether the offender or victim was a tribal member, and the state in which the crime occurred. Crimes committed in Indian country are often subject to concurrent jurisdiction between multiple criminal justice agencies. The Major Crimes Act (18 U.S.C. § 1153), as amended, grants concurrent federal jurisdiction for 16 major crimes committed by Native Americans occurring in Indian country. State jurisdiction for crimes committed in Indian country is primarily provided for under P.L. 280. Tribal courts maintain concurrent jurisdiction when federal or state jurisdiction is applied. State prosecutors’ offices generally do not have jurisdiction over crimes committed in Indian country due to the sovereign status of federally recognized tribes in the United States. However, state prosecutors’ offices in 16 states may exercise jurisdiction over crimes committed on tribal lands under P.L. 280. This law established state jurisdiction over offenses committed by or against American Indians in Indian country, including federally recognized reservations, tribal communities, and identified trust lands. P.L. 280 is mandatory for 6 states and optional for 10 states. Highlights � Ninety-three state court prosecutors’ offices in the 16 P.L. 280 states reported jurisdiction for felonies committed in Indian country under P.L. 280. � Seventy-three percent of offices with jurisdiction in Indian country reported prosecuting at least one felony case committed in Indian country. � Most offices in P.L. 280 states prosecuted at least one offense involving drugs (63%), domestic violence (60%), or aggravated assault (58%). � Eighteen offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states with jurisdiction for Indian country prosecuted at least one rape, and 12 offices prosecuted a homicide. � Of state prosecutors’ offices that reported jurisdiction for felony cases in Indian country under P.L. 280, 70% served judicial districts with populations of less than 100,000 residents. � Offices with jurisdiction for felony crimes committed in Indian country had an average operating budget of $5.2 million in 2007. Criminal jurisdic tion in I ndian countr y Tribal jurisdiction � Crimes committed by Native Americans in Indian country. Sentences are limited to a maximum 3-year sentence of incarceration per count and 9 years per case (124 U.S.C. 2258 § 234 (a) (b)). Federal jurisdiction � Pursuant to the Major Crimes Act of 1885. 18 U.S.C. § 1153 and subsequent amendments State jurisdiction � All crimes on tribal lands specified under Public Law 83-280. 18 U.S.C. § 1162 � Crimes committed on tribal lands in which neither the victim nor the offender is a tribal member. Note: Criminal jurisdiction in Indian country depends on several factors, including the identity of the defendant, victim, type of offense, and where the crime was committed. U.S. Department of Justice Office of Justice Programs Bureau of Justice Statistics June 2011, NCJ 234241 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201122 According to the 2002 Census of Tribal Justice Agencies, 94 of the 123 responding tribes in mandatory P.L. 280 states relied on state courts. The 2002 Census was limited to American Indian tribes in the lower 48 states, so tribes in Alaska were excluded. The Census also found that 19 of 90 reporting tribes in optional P.L. 280 states relied on state courts (table 3.1). The federal government retains criminal jurisdiction for major crimes committed in Indian country in the remaining states where P.L. 280 does not apply. States retain jurisdiction for non-Indian crimes (those in which neither the offender nor the victim is a tribal member) committed in Indian country.* In 2007, 1,548 state court prosecutors’ offices were in states not affected by P.L. 280 and were excluded from this report. The 93 state prosecutors’ offices reporting jurisdiction under P.L. 280 in mandatory and optional states represent 14% of all state prosecutors’ offices in states affected by P.L. 280. Nearly all of these served districts that overlapped with or were adjacent to tribal lands (figure 3.1). Approximately a fifth of state prosecutors in mandatory P.L. 280 states reported jurisdiction for crimes committed in Indian country P.L. 280 gave select states legal jurisdiction over tribal members to prosecute crimes occurring on the reservation under existing state laws. These mandatory P.L. 280 states include California, Minnesota (except the Red Lake Reservation), Nebraska, Oregon (except the Warm Springs Reservation), Wisconsin, and Alaska (table 3.2). *Some tribes have been affected by states that have received a federal mandate to exercise jurisdiction outside of P.L. 280, e.g., through state-wide enactments, restoration acts, or land claims settlement acts (Tribal Court Clearinghouse, 2010, www.tribal-institute.org/ lists/jurisdiction.htm). Table 3.1 Number of tribes participating in the Census of Tribal Justice Agencies in Indian Country, by P.L. 280 status, type of court systems, and state, 2002 Number of tribes using— Participating in census Tribal justice systems Indigenous courts CFR courtsa Tribal courts Relying on state courtsb Mandatory states 123 39 8 9 37 94 California 88 7 2 7 7 74 Minnesota 12 12 3 0 12 4 Nebraska 4 3 0 2 3 2 Oregon 8 8 1 0 8 6 Wisconsin 11 9 2 0 7 8 Optional states 90 80 13 11 74 19 Arizona 17 16 3 0 16 0 Florida 1 0 0 0 0 1 Idaho 4 4 1 0 4 1 Iowa 1 0 0 0 0 1 Montana 6 6 1 0 5 0 Nevada 16 14 1 4 13 6 North Dakota 3 3 0 0 3 0 South Dakota 9 9 0 2 9 0 Utah 4 2 0 2 2 2 Washington 29 26 7 3 22 8 Note: The 2002 Census of Tribal Justice Agencies was limited to American Indian tribes in the lower 48 states. Source: Table reproduced from Census of Tribal Justice Agencies in Indian Country, 2002, NCJ 205332, BJS Web, December 2005. aCourt of Federal Regulations (CFR) operated by the Bureau of Indian Affairs (BIA). bTribes that rely on state court for jusidical services (e.g., felony courts, court-ordered treatment, and child support enforcement). Table 3.2 State prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction for crimes committed in Indian country, by P.L. 280 status and state, 2007 Number of offices— All prosecutors’ offices in P.L. 280 states* With jurisdiction for felony cases occurring in Indian country under P.L. 280 Prosecuting at least one felony case All P.L. 280 states 672 93 68 Mandatory states 294 56 47 Alaska 1 1 -- California 48 23 21 Minnesota 76 15 15 Nebraska 81 3 1 Oregon 31 7 4 Wisconsin 57 7 6 Optional states 378 37 21 Arizona 11 1 1 Florida 16 1 1 Idaho 34 6 4 Iowa 93 1 1 Montana 46 5 1 Nevada 15 2 0 North Dakota 43 2 1 South Dakota 58 1 1 Utah 26 3 2 Washington 36 15 9 Note: The 2007 Census of State Court Prosecutors included 2,330 offices, 66% (1,548) of which were located in states not affected by P.L. 280, and therefore were excluded from all analyses. --No information reported. *Excludes data missing for 110 offices. 23 M an da to ry P .L . 2 80 st at es Op tio na l P .L . 2 80 st at es In di an re se rv at io n (U .S . C en su s B ur ea u) Pr os ec ut or s’ o� ce s r ep or tin g ju ris di ct io n in In di an Co un try u nd er P .L . 2 80 Fi g u r e 3 .1 St at e p ro se cu to rs ’ o ffi ce s re p o rt in g ju ri sd ic ti o n in In d ia n c o u n tr y u n d er P .L . 2 80 , 2 00 7 N ot e: P ro se cu to rs ’ o ffi ce s i n no n- P.L . 2 80 st at es a re n ot sh ow n. So ur ce : B ur ea u of Ju st ic e St at ist ic s Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201124 In 2007, 19% of all state prosecutors’ offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states reported jurisdiction for felony cases occurring in Indian country. P.L. 280 permitted other states to acquire either complete or partial jurisdiction over crimes committed in Indian country at their option: Arizona, Florida, Idaho, Iowa, Montana, Nevada, North Dakota, South Dakota, Utah, and Washington. Ten percent of all prosecutors’ offices in optional P.L. 280 states reported jurisdiction for felony cases in Indian country in 2007. About three-quarters of offices with P.L. 280 jurisdiction prosecuted a felony case from Indian country in 2007 Sixty-eight of the 93 prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction in Indian country reported prosecuting at least one felony case committed in Indian country in 2007. Forty-seven offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states reported prosecuting at least one offense committed in Indian country, and 21 offices in optional P.L. 280 states reported prosecuting at least one offense committed in Indian country in 2007. Most offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states with jurisdiction for felony offenses in Indian country also reported prosecuting at least one drug-related crime (42 of 56 offices), domestic violence offense (40), aggravated assault (38), parole or probation violation (31), or a crime involving sexual assault or sexual abuse (30) (figure 3.2). Offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states with jurisdiction for Indian country also reported prosecuting serious felony offenses, including 18 offices that prosecuted at least one rape committed in Indian country and 12 offices that prosecuted a homicide. Prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction in Indian country had an average of 16 assistant prosecutors on staff The 2007 National Census of State Prosecutors collected operational and administrative information from state prosecutors’ offices, including budgets, staffing, and caseload. Offices reporting jurisdiction for crimes committed under P.L. 280 were not asked to disaggregate office resources or operations by whether they were directed toward crimes committed in Indian country or elsewhere in the judicial district. The census asked respondents to provide or estimate the total number of felony cases closed in 2007. The survey did not ask respondents to provide information on the number of cases that arose from crimes committed in Indian country. This section describes the entire operations of the state prosecutors’ offices reporting jurisdiction under P.L. 280, not operations specific to crimes committed in Indian country. Homicide Rape Robbery Sexual assault/abuse Parole/probation violation Aggravated assault Domestic violence Drug-related All felony cases prosecuted in Indian Country, under P.L. 280 Optional P.L. 280 Mandatory P.L. 280 Number of o�ces 47 21 42 17 40 16 38 16 31 15 30 10 21 8 18 5 12 4 Figure 3.2 State prosecutors’ offices reporting prosecution of specific crimes in Indian country, by P.L. 280 status, 2007 State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 25 Most (71) state prosecutors’ offices that reported jurisdiction for felony cases occurring in Indian country under P.L. 280 served judicial districts with populations of less than 100,000 residents or were part-time offices. In mandatory P.L. 280 states, 7 of the 56 offices with jurisdiction in Indian country served districts with 250,000 or more residents (table 3.3). Offices with jurisdiction for felony crimes committed in Indian country had an average 2007 budget of $5.2 million, or an expenditure of about $31 per district resident. The median budget was $722,000. The office staff included an average of 16 assistant prosecutors, 3 victim advocates, 4 legal services staff, and 19 support staff (table 3.4). Offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states reported an average of 61 total staff, including 19 assistant prosecutors, 8 investigators, and 22 support staff. Offices in optional P.L. 280 states reported an average of 38 total staff, 11 assistant prosecutors, 1 investigator, and 14 support staff. Offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states, reported closing a similar number of felony cases in 2007 compared to optional state offices. State prosecutors’ offices in optional P.L. 280 states closed 1,784 felony cases in 2007, while offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states closed 1,699 felony cases. Table 3.3 Type of state prosecutors’ offices reporting jurisdiction in Indian country, by P.L. 280 status, 2007 Total P.L. 280 Status Population served Mandatory Optional All offices 93 56 37 Full-time offices serving a judicial district with— 1 million or more residents 4 2 2 250,000 to 999,999 5 5 0 100,000 to 249,999 13 8 5 99,999 or fewer 65 37 28 Part-time offices* 6 4 2 *Part-time offices are defined as those that reported a part-time chief prosecutor in 2007. Table 3.4 Budget, staffing, and caseload of state prosecutors’ offices, by P.L. 280 status, 2007 Total P.L. 280 status Mandatory Optional Mean Median Mean Median Mean Median Total resident population served 156,495 28,893 177,407 28,965 124,846 28,606 Total operating budget $5,173,831 $722,208 $6,560,838 $735,735 $3,074,577 $670,000 Budget per resident population served $31 $26 $35 $27 $25 $24 Total staffa 51 12 61 12 38 12 Chief prosecutor 1 1 1 1 1 1 Assistant prosecutors 16 3 19 4 11 3 Civil prosecutors 2 0 1 0 4 1 Supervisors 2 1 2 0 2 1 Managers 1 0 1 0 0 0 Victim advocates 3 1 3 1 2 1 Legal services 4 0 3 0 4 1 Investigators 5 0 8 0 1 0 Support staff 19 3 22 4 14 3 Felony cases closedb 1,733 300 1,699 300 1,784 275 Note: Statistics include imputed data for some offices. Data were missing for 3 offices that did not provide total operating budget, 1 office that did not provide staffing information, and 6 offices that did not provide the number of felony cases closed. See Methodology for more information. aAll staff statistics are presented as full-time equivalent staff, calculated as the number of full-time staff plus 50% of the number of half time staff. bIncludes all cases charged as a felony that had a judgment of conviction, acquittal, or dismissal, with or without prejudice, entered by the court. Cases closed include all felony cases closed by the prosecutors’ offices and include an unknown number of cases committed in Indian country. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201126 Methodology The 2007 National Census of State Court Prosecutors (NCSP-07) surveyed 2,330 chief prosecutors in the United States who handled felony cases in state courts of general jurisdiction. The census did not include municipal attorneys or county attorneys who primarily operate in courts of limited jurisdiction. This report describes characteristics of offices that reported jurisdiction for crimes committed in Indian country under P.L. 280 in 2007. Most (66%) state court prosecutors’ offices included in the 2007 census were in states not affected by P.L. 280 and are excluded from this report. The operational and administrative characteristics described in this report represent the functions of the entire office and are not restricted to those functions, staff, budget, or other resources specifically devoted to crimes committed in Indian country, unless otherwise noted. Data Imputations BJS relied on previously reported data and valid office characteristics to impute values for critical variables where missing. These critical variables, found in Table 3.4, include the total operating budget, total staff, full- or part-time status of chief prosecutor, number of assistant prosecutors, and number of felony cases closed. Critical variables that were missing in 2007 were imputed from the same office’s response to the 2001 Census of State Prosecutors wherever possible. For each jurisdiction with valid 2001 and 2007 data, an adjustment ratio was calculated as the ratio of the critical variable’s 2001 value to its 2007 value. All ratios greater than the 90th percentile were discarded for imputation purposes. For those offices missing 2007 data, a hot deck imputation procedure was employed to impute the adjustment ratio value from the office’s nearest neighbor in terms of state and population size. Where there were no suitable donors in the same state, a donor of similar population size was used. The 2001 data were then adjusted using the imputed adjustment ratio to create the imputed 2007 value for the critical variable where missing. This procedure was followed for 3 offices missing total operating budget, 1 office missing staffing information, and 6 offices missing the number of felony cases closed. Reference Census of Tribal Justice Agencies in Indian Country, 2002, NCJ 205332, BJS Web, `December 2005. Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 27 Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 Todd D. Minton, BJS Statistician At midyear 2009, a total of 2,176 inmates were confined in Indian country jails, a 1.9% increase from the 2,135 inmates confined at midyear 2008 (figure 4.1). This count was based on data from 80 facilities, including jails, confinement facilities, detention centers, and other correctional facilities, that were in operation in Indian country at midyear 2009. For 2008, the number of inmates was based on data for 82 facilities in operation at midyear 2008. The number of inmates held in Indian country jails between 2004 and 2009 increased by 25% from 1,745 inmates to 2,176. The number of jails in Indian country has increased between 2004 and 2009 The Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS) collected data from 68 correctional facilities in Indian country in 2004, from 79 in 2007, 82 in 2008, and 80 in 2009. The survey was not conducted in 2005 and 2006. Over the 5-year period, a number of facilities closed and new facilities became operational. Eleven facilities permanently closed between 2004 and 2009, and a total of 21 facilities were newly Highlights � The number of inmates confined in Indian country jails increased by 1.9% between midyear 2008 and 2009, reaching 2,176 inmates. � Between June 2008 and June 2009, the average daily jail population in Indian country increased by 12%, and the percentage of occupied bed space increased from 64.2% to 73.5%. � Eleven jails (14% of all facilities) held 51% of inmates confined at midyear 2009. � During June 2009, the number of inmates admitted to Indian country jails (11,357) was about 5 times the size of the average daily population (2,124). � The expected average length of stay increased by a half day from 5.1 days during June 2008 to 5.6 days during June 2009. � Indian country jail authorities reported no deaths in custody between July 1, 2008, and June 30, 2009, down from 4 reported deaths during the 12-month period ending June 30, 2008. � Attempted suicides by inmates declined from 78 in 2008 to 56 in 2009. � Indian country jails held fewer inmates for domestic violence at midyear 2009 (252), continuing the downward trend in the number held for this offense since 2007 (362). � The percentage of certified correctional officers working in Indian country jails increased steadily, from 63% at midyear 2007 to 79% at midyear 2009. U.S. Department of Justice Office of Justice Programs Bureau of Justice Statistics June 2011, NCJ 232223 0 400 800 1,200 1,600 2,000 2,400 Number of inmates 20092008200720042003200220012000 At midyear Figure 4.1 Inmates confined in Indian country jails, midyear 2000-2004 and 2007-2009 Note: The Survey of Jails in Indian Country was not conducted in 2005 and 2006. Midyear count is the number of inmates held on the last weekday in June. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201128 constructed. BJS estimated inmate population counts for 7 facilities in 2004 and 4 facilities in 2007 that did not respond to the surveys. All known operating facilities responded to the 2008 and 2009 surveys. (See Methodology for additional details on facility counts and participation in the surveys.) (See Methodology in Jails in Indian Country, 2009, NCJ 232223, BJS Web, February 2010, for additional details on facility counts and participation in the surveys.) On an average day in June, the percentage of occupied bed space increased from 64.2% to 73.5% At midyear 2009, the 80 jail facilities in Indian country were rated to hold 2,891 inmates, down from 2,963 in 82 facilities during the same period in 2008 (table 4.1). The average daily population (ADP) in June—the population measure used to calculate percent of capacity occupied—increased by nearly 12%, from 1,903 inmates (June 2008) to 2,124 (June 2009), while the capacity to hold inmates decreased by 2%. Consequently, the percentage of rated capacity occupied in Indian country jails increased from 64% to 73% during the period. On June 30, 2009, the 80 facilities held a total of 2,176 inmates and were operating at 75% of rated capacity, remaining relatively stable since 2007. From June 2004 to June 2009, the overall number of beds (or rated capacity) grew at a faster rate (34%) than the the inmate population (25%). Small number of jails held more than half of the inmate population Eleven jails held more than half (51%) of the total inmate population at midyear 2009 (table 4.2). Between midyear 2008 and midyear 2009, the population in these jails increased by 247 inmates (29%). In 2008, 9 of the 11 facilities held the majority of jail inmates in Indian country. Over the 365-day period, 6 jails that held the majority of inmates in Indian country in 2008 experienced large declines in their jail populations. The combined decrease in the size of the jail population in these facilities was 33% (90 inmates) from midyear 2008 to midyear 2009. Among the 11 facilities holding the majority of inmates in 2009, the Gila River Department of Rehabilitation and Supervision - Adult facility reported the largest decline (30 inmates or 17%) in the number of jail inmates. The jail population in this facility has decreased by 92 inmates (38%) from its peak of 241 inmates reported at midyear 2007. Table 4.1 Inmates, rated capacity, and percent of capacity occupied in Indian country jails, 2004 and 2007–2009 2004 2007 2008 2009 Number of inmates Midyeara 1,745 2,163 2,135 2,176 ADPb 1,622 2,046 1,903 2,124 Rated capacity 2,162 2,900 2,963 2,891 Percent of capacity occupiedc Midyear 80.7% 74.6% 72.1% 75.3% ADP 75.0 70.6 64.2 73.5 Number of operating facilities 68 79 82 80 aMidyear count is the number of inmates held on the last weekday in June. bAverage daily population (ADP) is the sum of the number of inmates held on each day in June, divided by 30. cPopulation as a percent of capacity occupied is calculated by dividing the population count of a facility by its rated capacity and multiplying by 100. Table 4.2 Jails in Indian country that held the majority of inmates in 2009 compared to 2008, by facility Custody population at midyear* Change in population Facility 2008 2009 Number Percent Total, 11 facilities 859 1,106 247 29% Tohono O’odham Adult Detention Center (AZ) 137 192 55 40% Gila River Department of Rehabilitation and Supervision - Adult (AZ) 179 149 -30 -17 San Carlos Department of Corrections and Rehabilitation - Adult and Juvenile Detention (AZ) 88 147 59 67 Truxton Canyon Adult Detention Center (AZ) 39 105 66 169 White Mountain Apache Detention Center (AZ) 101 95 -6 -6 Oglala Sioux Tribal Offenders Facility (SD) 52 95 43 83 Standing Rock Law Enforcement and Adult Detention Center (ND) 71 93 22 31 Nisqually Adult Corrections (WA) 59 73 14 24 Menominee Tribal Detention Facility (WI) 54 53 -1 -2 Navajo Department of Corrections - Shiprock Police Department and Adult Detention (NM) 46 52 6 13 Laguna Tribal Police and Detention Center (NM) 33 52 19 58 Note: Based on facilities that held the most inmates on June 30, 2009. *Midyear count is the number of inmates held on the last weekday in June. Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 29 Two facilities, the Truxton Canyon Adult Detention Center and the Laguna Tribal Police and Detention Center, were among the 11 facilities holding the majority of jail inmates in 2009. These 2 facilities were not among the 11 facilities holding the majority of inmates in 2008. (See Jails in Indian Country, 2008, BJS Web, December 2008.) The Truxton Canyon Adult Detention Center reported the largest increase in the inmate population (66 inmates or 169%) between midyear 2008 and midyear 2009. The Laguna Tribal Police and Detention Center increased by 58% (19 inmates) between 2008 and 2009. Based on the 80 facilities responding to the survey in both 2008 and 2009, the overall change in the inmate population (up 45 inmates) was relatively small. Thirty-three facilities, which were mostly the larger facilities, accounted for this increase (not shown in table). Change in the size of the jail population in Indian country was varied. More than half of the 80 jails experienced either a decline (40 jails) or no change (7 jails) in the size of their inmate population over the 12-month period ending midyear 2009. Overall, the 50% increase (415 inmates) in the jail population in 33 jails was offset by a 30% decline (370 inmates) in 40 jails. The use of jail space varied by facility size Indian country jails rated to hold 25 to 49 inmates were operating at 89% of their rated capacity on June 30, 2009, and at 79% on an average day in June. An average day in June was based on the ADP, or the sum of the numbers held on each day in June divided by 30. In contrast, the lowest percentage of capacity occupied during June 2009 was among the 11 small jails rated to hold fewer than 10 inmates. These facilities were operating at 21% of rated capacity at midyear and at 17% of capacity on an average day in June 2009 (figure 4.2). Compared to facilities in all other size categories, the large jails with a rated capacity of 50 or more inmates reported the only increase in occupied bed space between 2008 and 2009. The percentage of capacity occupied in these jails increased from 51% to 69% during the 12 months ending at midyear 2009, and from 49% to 73% on an average day in June 2008 and 2009. The amount of bed space occupied was also measured based on a facility’s most crowded day in June. Nearly half (38 facilities) of the 80 facilities in Indian country were operating above rated capacity on the most crowded day in June (table 4.3). Of those Table 4.3 Number of Indian country jails, by percent of rated capacity occupied, June 2009 Number of jails Percent of capacity occupieda Midyearb ADPc Peakd Less than 25% 17 20 7 25-49% 15 11 8 50-74% 19 21 15 75-100% 11 15 12 More than 100% 18 13 38 aPopulation as a percent of capacity occupied is calculated by dividing the population count of a facility by its rated capacity and multiplying by 100. bMidyear count is the number of inmates held on the last weekday in June. cAverage daily population (ADP) is the sum of the number of inmates held on each day in June, divided by 30. dPeak population is the population held on the day in June in which the custody population of a facility was the largest. 0 20 40 60 80 100 120 140 Peak 50 or more25 to 4910 to 24Fewer than 10 inmatesTotal Percent of capacity occupied ADP Midyear Figure 4.2 Rated capacity occupied, by type of inmate count, June 2009 Note: Rated capacity is the maximum number of beds or inmates assigned by a rating official. Midyear count is the number of inmates held on the last weekday in June. Average daily population (ADP) is the sum of the number of inmates held on each day in June divided by 30. Peak population is the population held on the day in June in which the custody population of a facility was the largest. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201130 facilities, 18 were operating above rated capacity on June 30, and 13 were operating above rated capacity on an average day during June 2009. High volumes of admissions of inmates were processed through Indian country jails Eighty Indian country jails admitted 11,357 persons during June 2009, up slightly from 11,149 admissions in 81 facilities during June 2008 (table 4.4). The number of admissions grew by 1.6% in the 79 facilities that reported data on admissions in both June 2009 (11,323) and June 2008 (11,147) (not shown in table). Admissions to facilities rated to hold between 25 to 49 inmates accounted for about 48% (5,503) of all admissions in June 2009, down from 59% of all admissions in June 2008. The largest Indian country jails accounted for less than 20% of all facilities and reported a total increase of nearly 75% in the number of jail admissions during the 12-month period. Admissions to the largest Indian country jails increased from 1,915 inmates to 3,342 from June 2008 to June 2009. The 15 jails rated to hold 50 or more inmates had the highest average number of admissions per month (233), compared to jails in all other size categories (not shown in table). Inmate deaths and attempted suicides in Indian country jails declined Indian country jail authorities reported no deaths in custody between July 1, 2008, and June 30, 2009, down from 4 reported deaths during the 12-month period ending June 30, 2008. Attempted suicides by inmates declined from 78 in 2008 to 56 in 2009. Expected length of stay was 5.6 days for Indian country jail inmates in June 2009 During June 2009, the expected average length of stay for inmates confined in Indian country jails was 5.6 days, up from 5.1 days during June 2008. Length of stay is the time held in custody from admission to release. The expected length of stay for inmates was the highest (9.1 days) Table 4.4 Admissions and expected length of stay in Indian country jails during June, by facility size, June 2009 Facility sizea Number of facilities ADPb Estimated June admissions Expected average length of stayc Total 80 2,124 11,357 5.6 days Fewer than 10 inmates 11 9 133 2.1 10 to 24 24 276 2,379 3.5 25 to 49 30 820 5,503 4.5 50 or more 15 1,018 3,342 9.1 Note: Detail may not sum to total due to rounding. aBased on the rated capacity, the maximum number of beds or inmates assigned by a rating official. bAverage daily population (ADP) is the sum of the number of inmates held on each day in June, divided by 30. cExpected length of stay was calculated by dividing the average daily population (ADP) by the number of June admissions, and multiplying by 30. See Methodology in Jails in Indian Country, 2009 for details on estimating expected length of stay. Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 31 Table 4.5 Number of inmates confined in Indian country jails, by demographic characteristic, conviction status, and offense, midyear 2002, 2004, and 2007–2009 Number of inmates held at midyeara Percent of inmates held at midyear Characteristic 2000 2002 2004 2007 2008 2009 2000 2002 2004 2007 2008 2009 Total 1,775 2,006 1,745 1,996 2,135 2,176 100% 100% 100% 100% 100% 100% Sex Male 1,421 1,618 1,346 1,582 1,678 1,754 80% 81% 77% 79% 79% 81% Female 354 388 398 414 457 422 20 19 23 21 21 19 Age group/sex Adults 1,498 1,699 1,546 1,743 1,882 1,919 84% 85% 89% 87% 88% 88% Male 1,214 1,399 1,222 1,415 1,498 1,571 68 70 70 71 70 72 Female 284 300 324 328 384 348 16 15 19 16 18 16 Juveniles 277 307 198 253 253 257 16 15 11 13 12 12 Male 207 219 124 167 180 183 12 11 7 8 8 8 Female 70 88 74 86 73 74 4 4 4 4 3 3 Conviction status Convicted 1,072 1,120 966 1,116 1,340 1,496 61% 57% 58% 59% 63% 69% Unconvicted 689 857 697 763 776 680 39 43 42 41 37 31 Type of offense Domestic violence ... 291 257 362 307 252 ...% 15% 18% 20% 15% 12% Assault ... ... 190 233 308 299 ... ... 13 13 15 15 Rape or sexual assault ... ... 34 45 42 42 ... ... 2 2 2 2 Other violence ... ... 79 108 177 168 ... ... 6 6 9 8 DWI/DUIb 274 226 195 137 184 229 17 11 14 8 9 11 Drug law violation 133 126 104 132 104 107 8 6 7 7 5 5 Other ... ... 569 804 954 955 ... ... 40 44 46 47 Offense not reported ... ... 317 175 59 124 / / / / / / Note: Detailed characteristics may not be equal to the total number of confined inmates because of incomplete data. See appendix tables 1-3 in Jails in Indian Country, 2009, NCJ 232223, BJS Web, February 2011, for a list of all facilities and inmate characteristics. aMidyear count is the number of inmates held on the last weekday in June. bIncludes driving while intoxicated and driving while under the influence of drugs or alcohol. ...Not collected. /Not reported. in facilities that were rated to hold 50 or more inmates, down from 10.3 days in June 2008. Inmates held in jails rated to hold less than 10 inmates experienced the shortest expected length of stay (2.1 days). Inmate characteristics remain relatively unchanged; the number held for domestic violence declined Inmate characteristics by sex, age, and offense have changed in absolute numbers since 2000 (table 4.5). However, the distribution within most categories remained stable between 2000 and 2008, with a change in the distribution of inmates by sex, conviction status, and offense type at midyear 2009. Adult males accounted for the largest portion of the inmate population in Indian country jails during the decade. The female jail population had small but steady increases from midyear 2000 to 2008, with a nearly 8% decrease in the size of this population between midyear 2008 and midyear 2009. Except for one juvenile female inmate, the decline was entirely among the adult female jail population. The percentage of convicted inmates increased from 57% in 2002 to 69% in 2009. Inmates confined for a violent offense made up about 37% of the jail population at midyear 2009, down from 41% at midyear 2008. Most (75%) of this decline was among the population held for domestic violence. Domestic violence (12%) and simple or aggravated assault (15%) accounted for the largest percentage of violent offenders held in 2009, followed by unspecified violent offenses (8%) and rape or sexual assault (2%). Since peaking at midyear 2007, the percentage of inmates held for domestic violence has steadily declined, from 20% in 2007 to 12% in 2009. The Gila River Department of Rehabilitation and Supervision - Adult accounted for a large portion of the decline in domestic violence offenders between 2007 and 2009. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201132 It reported a 38% decrease in the confined inmate population between midyear 2007 (241) and midyear 2009 (149), and a 74% decline in the number of inmates held for a domestic violence (from 180 inmates in 2007 to 46 in 2009). The number of certified correctional officers and in-service training steadily increased Seventy-nine Indian country jails employed 1,332 persons at midyear 2009 (table 4.6). About 69% (916) of all personnel were jail operations staff, including correctional officers and other staff who spent more than 50% of their time supervising inmates. The remaining 416 jail personnel included administrative employees, educational staff, technical or professional staff, clerical, maintenance, or food service staff, and other job functions. Overall, the ratio of inmates to jail operations employees was 2.4 inmates to 1 employee at midyear 2009, remaining relatively stable since 2008 (2.3 to 1) and 2004 (2.5 to 1). Seventy-six facilities reported that 710 (79%) correctional officers received basic detention officer certification, up from 69% in 2008 and 63% in 2007 (not shown). Seventy-four facilities reported that 750 (84%) correctional officers received 40 hours of in-service training, up from 74% in 2008 and 70% in 2007. Table 4.6 Persons employed in Indian country jails, by job function, midyear 2009 Job function Number Percent Totala 1,332 100% Administrativeb 136 10.2% Jail operations 916 68.8 Educational staff 29 2.2 Technical/professional 51 3.8 Clerical/maintenance/food service 173 13.0 Number of inmates per jail operations staff 2.4 aIncludes 27 other persons with unspecified functions not shown in table. bIncludes jail administrators, assistants, and other personnel who work in an administrative capacity more than 50% of the time. Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 33 Methodology The Annual Survey of Jails in Indian Country (SJIC) includes all known Indian country correctional facilities operated by tribal authorities or the Bureau of Indian Affairs (BIA), U.S. Department of the Interior. The survey was conducted in June 2009, and included the number of inmates and percent of capacity occupied based on the ADP, midyear population, and peak population in facilities in June 2009. (See table 10 in Jails in Indian Country, 2009, BJS Web, February 2011.) Through a cooperative agreement with the Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS), Westat, Inc. conducted the SJIC to describe all adult and juvenile jail facilities and detention centers in Indian country. For this report, Indian country includes reservations, pueblos, rancherias, and other appropriate areas (18 U.S.C.§ 1151). The reference date for the survey is June 30, 2009. Annually, BIA provides BJS a list of Indian country jail facilities, including detention centers, jails, and other correctional facilities operated by tribal authorities or BIA. BJS uses this list to update its existing roster of jails in Indian country. BJS obtains data from administrators of Indian country jails by mailed questionnaires and through follow-up phone calls and facsimiles. In 2004, BJS contacted administrators in 70 facilities to participate in the survey. BJS received responses from 61 facilities; 7 did not respond, and 2 facilities were non-operational. In 2007, the BJS roster consisted of 86 facilities. Seventy-nine of the facility administrators responded to the survey; 4 did not respond, and BJS found that 3 facilities were non- operational. In 2008, BJS’s roster of Indian country jails consisted of 85 facilities. BJS received responses from 82 facility administrators; there were no nonrespondents, and 3 facilities were non-operational. For 2009, the BJS roster consisted of 86 facilities. BJS received responses from 80 facility administrators; there were no nonrespondents, and 6 facilities were non-operational. For comparison over time, BJS estimated data on inmate populations for the 7 facilities in 2004 and 4 facilities in 2008 that did not respond to the surveys. Expected length of stay The stock-flow ratio method was used to measure the expected average length of stay for inmates held during June 2009 in the 80 Indian country jails that responded to stock and flow items in the survey: Stock—average daily population Flow—inmate admissions during June 2009 Stock-flow ratio in June 2009 (2,124/11,357=0.187) Expected length of stay in days (0.187 × 30)—is the average number of days held in custody from admission to release. Indian country is a statutory term that includes all lands within an Indian reservation, dependent Indian communities, and Indian trust allotments (18 U.S.C. § 1151). Courts interpret Section 1151 to include all lands held in trust for tribes or their members. (See United States v. Roberts, 185 F.3d 1125 (10th Cir. 1999).) Tribal authority to imprison American Indian offenders is limited to one year per offense by statute (25 U.S.C. § 1302), a $5,000 fine, or both. Tribal law enforcement agencies act as first responders to both felony and misdemeanor crimes. For most of Indian country, the federal government provides felony law enforcement concerning crimes by or against Indians. Certain areas of Indian country are under Public Law 83-280, as amended. P.L. 280 conferred jurisdiction on certain states over Indian country and suspended enforcement of the Major Crimes Act (18 U.S.C. § 1153) and the General Crimes Act (18 U.S.C. § 1152) in those areas. Indian tribes retain concurrent jurisdiction to enforce laws in Indian country where P.L. 280 applies. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201134 Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 35 Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System Mark Motivans, Ph.D., and Howard Snyder, Ph.D., BJS Statisticians The federal criminal justice response to tribal youth varies by the state in which the offense occurred, the nature of the offense, the availability of community- and confinement-based services, and discretionary decisions made by tribal, state, and federal justice agencies. Cases involving tribal youth in the federal system may result in 1) a delinquency adjudication and court-ordered supervision and out-of-home placement, or 2) the youth being transferred to adult status and prosecuted and sentenced as an adult. This summary describes the federal response to tribal youth during the case-processing stages from investigation to corrections. In this report, a federal juvenile delinquent is a person who has committed an offense while under age 18, and the federal prosecutor has certified a federal basis for jurisdiction. Juvenile and youth are used interchangeably in this report. The number of tribal youth in matters concluded by federal prosecutors and the total number of tribal youth prosecuted decreased from 2003 to 2008 (figure 5.1). Tribal youth in matters concluded by federal prosecutors dropped to 115 in 2008, down from 230 in 2003. Highlights � In 2008, relatively few juveniles were referred to federal prosecutors (315 out of 178,570 suspects) or admitted to federal prison jurisdiction (156 out 71,663 offenders). � Tribal youth (70) comprised nearly half of juveniles (152) handled by the federal courts in 2008. � Federal judicial districts of Arizona, Montana, South Dakota, New Mexico, and North Dakota accounted for 94% of tribal youth investigated, 92% of those prosecuted, and 88% of those admitted to federal prison jurisdiction in 2008. � In 2008, about 72% of tribal youth were investigated for violent offenses, including sexual abuse (35%), assault (20%), and murder (17%). � About 40% of matters involving tribal youth were declined by federal prosecutors in 2008. � A greater share of cases involving tribal youth in U.S. district courts were terminated by conviction (91%) than by dismissal (9%). � From 1994 to 2008, the lowest number of tribal (72) and non-tribal youth (84) admitted to the jurisdiction of federal prison authorities occurred in 2008. � Admissions to federal prison jurisdiction among tribal youth declined 10% per year from 1999 to 2008, while non-tribal youth admissions declined 12% per year. � In 2008, tribal youth served an average of 26 months under federal jurisdiction, which was more than double the tribal justice system maximum sentence of 12 months. U.S. Department of Justice Office of Justice Programs Bureau of Justice Statistics June 2011, NCJ 234218 Findings presented in this report are mostly from a recent study conducted by The Urban Institute under a cooperative agreement with the Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS). The study was also sponsored by the Office of Juvenile Justice and Delinquency Prevention (OJJDP). See page 43 for more information. Figure 5.1 Tribal youth in matters concluded and in matters prosecuted by U.S. attorneys, 2000–2008 Number of tribal youth Fiscal year 0 50 100 150 200 250 Suspects in matters prosecuted Suspects in matters concluded 200820072006200520042003200220012000 Source: Urban Institute analysis. See Methodology for more information. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201136 Tracking tribal youth through the stages of the federal criminal case process The federal criminal justice system is not currently well- equipped to monitor how tribal juvenile offenders are processed across stages. There is a lack of unified, system-wide data standards in reporting how youth— especially tribal youth—are handled in the federal system. Juveniles or offenses committed in Indian country are not systematically tracked across the federal justice agencies. Researchers have to devise analytic methods to identify tribal youth using administrative data from each criminal justice stage (arrest, sentencing, and corrections). How is federal jurisdic tion over tribal juvenile delinquents determined? The determination of jurisdiction over offenses occurring in Indian country is first subject to whether state courts have jurisdiction based on Public Law 280 (P.L. 280).1 If a state has P. L. 280 status, jurisdiction over offenses occurring in Indian country lies with the state or tribal courts, not the federal courts. The determination of whether federal jurisdiction applies next depends on the offender and victim in the crime: � If the offender is a juvenile tribal member and the victim is also a tribal member, and the offense is 1 of 15 crimes covered by the Major Crimes Act then jurisdiction is with both the tribal and federal courts.2 � If the offender is a juvenile tribal member and the victim is a non-tribal member, and the crime is covered by the Major Crimes Act or federal enclave status, then federal and tribal courts have shared jurisdiction. The Assimilative Crimes Act permits state law to be applied in federal court where the Major Crimes Act does not apply but federal interest exists. � If the crime involves a non-tribal offender and a tribal member victim, then federal courts have exclusive jurisdiction. Once federal jurisdiction has been established, the Federal Juvenile Delinquency Act (FJDA) provides the procedures to bring the tribal youth to federal court. A federal juvenile delinquent is defined as a person who has committed an offense while less than 18 years old, but has not reached age 21 at sentencing. Juvenile and youth are used interchangeably in this report. How are juveniles handled in the federal justice system? Most juveniles, or persons under age 18, in the United States are handled in state or local courts, which have a separate juvenile justice system, rather than in the federal courts. Federal law permits handling of juveniles in the federal system only in limited circumstances. Apart from those committing crimes in Indian country or on military bases, juveniles that commit offenses as members of drug trafficking gangs, violent criminal gangs, or other federal offenses may be subject to federal jurisdiction. In these cases, the U.S. attorney for each district must certify to the district court that (1) the juvenile court or court of a state does not have jurisdiction or refuses to assume jurisdiction; 2) the state does not have available programs or services adequate for the needs of juveniles; or 3) the offense charged is a felony crime of violence or specified drug offenses, and there is substantial federal interest in the case. I n what circumstances are tribal and non- tribal juveniles transferred to adult status (for prosecution and sentencing as an adult rather than a juvenile delinquent)? Once federal jurisdiction has been determined and certification of delinquency established, a transfer hearing establishes the status of juveniles as to whether they will be transferred for prosecution as an adult. Felony crimes of violence or drug or firearm offenses trigger eligibility for adult transfer with certain age restrictions. Age thirteen is the minimum age for transfer to adult status for murder and assault, and for robbery, bank robbery, or aggravated sexual abuse with a firearm. An exception is crimes committed in Indian country where the tribe has opted not to permit prosecution of juveniles age 13 as adults. Age fifteen is the minimum age for transfer to adult status for committing any crime of violence (including physical force against a person or property). A juvenile can be housed in a Federal Bureau of Prisons (BOP) institution at age 18 if sentenced as an adult. BOP does not operate its own facilities for juveniles; rather, they contract with private entities and state and local governments for both secure and non-secure (community- based) juvenile facilities to house tribal and non-tribal youth under their jurisdiction. 1Congress passed Public Law 280 in 1953, which relinquishes the federal government of criminal and civil jurisdiction in certain states and places jurisdiction with those states. 2The Major Crimes Act provides federal jurisdiction over certain offenses committed by tribal members. (See Title 18 U.S.C. §§ 1152, 1153.) Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 37 Table 5.1 Reason for matters declined for prosecution with tribal youth suspects, 2005–2008 Reasons for declinations Fiscal year Matters concluded Number of declinations Case- relateda Suspect- relatedb No crime Referred to other authoritiesc OtherTotal 2005 172 69 100% 58% 10% 9% 13% 10% 2006 164 80 100% 61 10 10 13 6 2007 143 68 100% 47 15 10 18 10 2008 115 46 100% 50 7 15 20 8 aIncludes weak evidence, stale case, witness problems, or jurisdiction or venue problems. bIncludes age of offender and offender ‘s criminal history and drug/alcohol use. cIncludes pretrial alternative resolutions, such as pretrial diversion. Source: Urban Institute analysis of Executive Office for U.S. Attorneys, National LIONS data base, fiscal years 2005–2008. Investigation and Prosecution Tribal police are often the first to respond to a crime in Indian country. Offenses committed by tribal youth may be investigated by a combination of tribal police and federal law enforcement agencies. The federal Bureau of Investigation (FBI) and the Bureau of Indian Affairs (BIA) are the primary federal law enforcement agencies investigating tribal youth matters. Tribal youth commonly enter the federal justice system with an arrest for a warrant issued on either a complaint or juvenile information (written accusation made by the prosecutor). For serious offenses that may indicate a federal crime, the U.S. attorney’s office in the district is notified as is the juvenile’s parent/guardian. The juvenile must be taken before a U.S. magistrate as soon as possible, where charges are read and the juvenile is informed of rights. Federal prosecutors next determine if the matter should be adjudicated in federal courts, disposed by U.S. magistrate, or declined for prosecution. In 2008, 4 in 10 matters involving a tribal youth were declined by federal prosecutors During 2008, 40% of tribal youth in matters concluded were declined for further prosecution, which was lower than the 46% declination rate for non-tribal youth in 2008. However, the average declination rate for tribal youth (45%) was higher than for non- tribal youth (37%) from 2004 to 2008. The most common reason for declination of tribal youth matters in 2008 was case related (50%) (table 5.1). Case-related reasons included weak evidence, stale case, witness problems, and jurisdiction or venue problems (figure 5.2). Some declined matters involved tribal youth that were subsequently referred to other authorities for prosecution, such as to the tribe or the state where the tribe is located. The share of declinations for tribal youth that were referred to other authorities or received an alternative resolution increased from 13% of all declinations in 2005 to 20% in 2008. Among non-tribal youth, the most common reason for declination (71%) was that the suspect was a juvenile (not shown in table). Most tribal youth in matters referred to U.S. attorneys were prosecuted by federal prosecutors In 2008, 59% of tribal youth who were referred to federal prosecutors were prosecuted, which was higher than the 54% prosecution rate for non-tribal youth in 2008 (including matters disposed by U.S. magistrates). From 2004 to 2008, the averageprosecution rate for tribal youth (55%) was comparable to that of non-tribal youth (53%). Various factors go into the decision to prosecute a matter, including seriousness of the crime, strength of the evidence, youth’s criminal history and drug/alcohol use, tribal capacity to prosecute, and tribal preference. Tribes having concurrent jurisdiction with federal jurisdiction may have limitations on available secure placement options and treatment resources. The potential penalty that could be received if a matter was handled in tribal or state venues may also be considered.3 3The Indian Civil Rights Act (Title 25 U.S.C. § 1302(7)), for example, limited tribes in sentencing persons convicted of serious crimes to a maximum of 1 year in jail and a $5,000 fine. Recently, the Tribal Law and Order Act extended the maximum sentence that a tribe can impose to three years. Figure 5.2 Case-related reasons for matters declined for prosecution with tribal youth suspects, 2005–2008 Jurisdiction or venue problems Stale case Witness problems Weak evidence Percent of cases 77% 13% 8% 2% Source: Urban Institute analysis of Executive Office for U.S. Attorneys, National LIONS data base, fiscal years 2005–2008. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201138 Nearly 9 of 10 tribal youth admitted to Federal Bureau of Prisons jurisdiction from 2006 to 2008 came from five federal judicial districts From 2006 to 2008, 85% of tribal youth admitted to the jurisdiction of the Federal Bureau of Prisons (BOP) were from these five federal judicial districts: Arizona, Montana, New Mexico, North Dakota, and South Dakota (figure 5.3). The most recent tribal population data from the Bureau of Indian Affairs (2005) showed that these five districts contained 12% of the 590 federally recognized tribal entities and 35% of the more than 1.9 million total tribal enrollment population (table 5.2). Thirty-four percent of the enrolled tribal population under age 16 resided on or near reservations in these five federal judicial districts. Table 5.2 Federally recognized tribes and enrolled members, 2005 Tribal entities Tribal enrollment Tribal population under age 16 Federal judicial district Number Percent Number Percent District rank Number Percent of total enrollment District rank Total 590 100% 1,978,099 100% ~ 503,958 100% ~ Arizona 22 3.7% 269,778 13.6% 2 70,854 14.1% 2 New Mexico 25 4.2 174,199 8.8 3 43,234 8.6 4 South Dakota 8 1.4 115,513 5.8 5 27,534 5.5 6 Montana 8 1.4 66,962 3.4 6 14,957 3 9 North Dakota 6 1 58,220 2.9 8 13,851 2.7 10 All other districts 521 88.3 1,293,427 65.4 ~ 333,528 66.2 ~ ~Not available. Source: U.S. Department of the Interior, Bureau of Indian Affairs. American Indian Population and Labor Force Report, 2005, available at: http://www.bia.gov/ WhatWeDo/Knowledge/Reports/index.htm, calendar year 2005. 45–87 16–4416–44 1–151–15 0 District of Arizona (14%) District of New Mexico (12%) District of Montana (28%) District of North Dakota (4%) District of South Dakota (27%) Number of tribal youth admitted Figure 5.3 Tribal youth admitted to the jurisdiction of the Federal Bureau of Prisons, and five federal judicial districts that committed the majority of tribal youth, 2006–2008 Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics analysis of data from the Federal Bureau of Prisons, SENTRY database, fiscal years 2006–2008. Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 39 Adjudication and Sentencing Federal statutes provide for a youth’s release pending trial to a parent/ guardian, unless it is determined that detention is necessary to ensure a timely appearance or to ensure safety of juveniles or others (Title 18 U.S.C. § 5034). The federal pretrial services agency oversees supervision of the youth on pretrial release. For juveniles detained, a foster home or community-based facility near the youth’s home community is sought. Pretrial juveniles are not to be detained in facilities permitting regular contact with adult offenders nor with other juveniles who have been adjudicated. In 2008, 91% of cases terminated in U.S. district court involving tribal youth resulted in conviction Most (91%) tribal youth cases terminated ended in conviction in 2008. Most of the convictions were the result of a guilty plea (88%) than a determination of guilt at trial (3%). In comparison, 95% of non-tribal youth were convicted in 2008, with 91% resulting from guilty pleas and 5% following trial. From 2004 to 2008, the average conviction rate for tribal youth (92%) was higher than for non- tribal youth (87%). In juvenile adjudication proceedings, the judge has the discretion to impose an out-of-home placement, probation and conditions of probation, or restitution. The youth may also be transferred to adult status and prosecuted and sentenced as an adult. An adjudicated juvenile can receive up to 3 years of probation. The duration of a sentence for youth adjudicated delinquent to the jurisdiction of federal prison authorities depends on the age of the juvenile at disposition (see text box below). Juveniles under the age of 18 are not allowed to be placed in an institution in which the youth has regular contact with incarcerated adults. A juvenile can be housed in a Federal Bureau of Prisons (BOP) institution at the age of 21 if sentenced as a juvenile. The maximum time under federal jurisdiction of juveniles adjudicated delinquent depends on the age at disposition � If a juvenile was under 18 years of age at time of disposition, detention may not extend beyond the juvenile reaching age 21 (figure 5.4). � If a juvenile was between the ages of 18 and 21 at time of disposition, the maximum federal jurisdiction is 5 years. � Juveniles adjudicated delinquent and under the age of 21 are not to be detained in facilities permitting regular contact with adult convicts. At age 21, however, an adjudicated delinquent can be placed in an adult facility. � The term that an adjudicated delinquent receives may not exceed the maximum period of imprisonment authorized had the juvenile been an adult. Federal sentencing guidelines do not apply to adjudications of delinquency. 11 or younger 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 Maximum age in federal jurisdiction is 21 if age at disposition is under 18 years Age at disposition Maximum age of federal jurisdiction For disposition between ages 18 and 21, the maximum length of federal jurisdiction is 5 years Age of delinquent at disposition Figure 5.4 Maximum time under federal jurisdiction of juveniles adjudicated delinquent, by age at disposition Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201140 Corrections The number of tribal youth admitted to BOP jurisdiction increased from 107 in 1994 to a peak of 252 in 2000— a 136% increase due exclusively to the growth in tribal youth handled as adjudicated delinquents (figure 5.5). The number of tribal youth admitted to the BOP subsequently decreased from 252 in 2000 to 72 in 2008. In 2008, the number of tribal (72) and non-tribal youth (84) admitted to the jurisdiction of federal prison authorities was the lowest in the period from 1994 to 2008. From 1999 to 2008, the number of tribal youth admissions declined an annual average of 10%, and non-tribal admissions declined at an annual average of 12%. Tribal youth peaked at 252 admissions in 2000, and non- tribal youth peaked at 272 admissions in 1999 (figure 5.6). Most (88%) of the decline in tribal youth from 1999 to 2008 was due to a decrease in youth who had been adjudicated delinquent. Twelve percent of the decline was due to a decrease in tribal youth who had been transferred to adult status. In comparison, most of the decline for non-tribal youth admitted to the BOP over this period was comprised of juveniles who had been transferred to adult status. In 2008, 72% of tribal youth were admitted to BOP jurisdiction for a violent offense, including sexual abuse (29%), assault (25%), and murder (15%) (table 5.3). Tribal youth admitted for property offenses (mostly burglary) peaked in 2000 (66) and began to decline in 2001, dropping to 14 admissions in 2008. By 2008, tribal youth admitted to BOP jurisdiction for both property and violent offenses had declined to the lowest levels since 1999. Among non-tribal youth admitted to BOP jurisdiction, violent and drug offenses comprised the majority of offense types (not shown in table). Most tribal youth admitted to BOP jurisdiction from 1999 to 2008 had been adjudicated delinquent (83%), while most non-tribal youth had been prosecuted as adults (65%). 0 50 100 150 200 250 300 Tribal-transferred as adult Tribal-adjudicated delinquent 200820072006200520042003200220012000199919981997199619951994 Number of tribal youth Fiscal year Figure 5.5 Tribal youth admitted to the jurisdiction of the Federal Bureau of Prisons, by status at admission, 1994–2008 Note: Data for fiscal years 1999–2008 based on Urban Institute analysis of Federal Bureau of Prisons, SENTRY database. Data for fiscal years 1994–1998 based on BJS analysis of SENTRY data. 0 50 100 150 200 250 300 Non-tribal-transferred as adult Non-tribal-adjudicated delinquent 200820072006200520042003200220012000199919981997199619951994 Number of non-tribal youth Fiscal year Figure 5.6 Non-tribal youth admitted to the jurisdiction of the Federal Bureau of Prisons, by status at admission, 1994–2008 Note: Data for fiscal years 1999–2008 based on Urban Institute analysis of Federal Bureau of Prisons, SENTRY database. Data for fiscal years 1994–1998 based on BJS analysis of SENTRY data. Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 41 At yearend 2003, 298 tribal youth were in BOP facilities, including both juvenile contract and adult facilities In 2003, 74% of tribal youth were housed under BOP jurisdiction in Minnesota, Arizona, Utah, the Western District of Texas, and Colorado. BOP facilities (including contract facilities) were not located in the states that contained large tribal populations and had committed a large number of Indian country juveniles (South Dakota, North Dakota, Montana, and New Mexico). For example, tribal youth whose legal residence was South Dakota comprised over half of the juveniles in BOP facilities in Minnesota. Among tribal youth under BOP jurisdiction in 2003, most were committed for a violent felony offense, including homicide, manslaughter, serious sexual assault or abuse, and serious physical assault. In comparison, 185 tribal juveniles were in custody in 10 juvenile tribal facilities in 2002. (See American Indians and Crime, BJS Web, December 2004.) These tribal youth were confined mostly for misdemeanor (62%) and status offenses (29%); 10% of the youth were confined in tribal juvenile facilities for felony offenses. Table 5.3 Tribal youth admitted to the jurisdiction of the Federal Bureau of Prisons, 1999–2008 Year of commitment to BOP jurisdiction Commitment offense Total 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 2008 Total 1,909 241 252 219 234 212 231 208 164 76 72 Murder/Negligent manslaughter* 218 31 27 25 18 20 24 26 20 16 11 Assault 491 44 65 70 57 52 64 52 49 20 18 Robbery 51 7 5 9 4 7 9 4 3 1 2 Sexual abuse 441 55 52 33 65 46 55 57 40 17 21 Embezzlement 1 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 Burglary 442 62 66 59 61 53 43 42 30 12 14 Larceny 56 12 7 5 8 4 4 6 6 2 2 Motor vehicle theft 8 2 1 1 0 1 0 1 2 0 0 Arson and explosives 69 2 6 3 5 11 17 9 6 7 3 Other property offenses 38 13 6 6 4 1 3 3 1 1 0 Other drug felonies 3 0 1 0 0 1 0 1 0 0 0 Weapon offenses 9 1 2 0 2 1 2 1 0 0 0 Nonviolent sex offenses 36 4 4 1 4 7 7 3 5 0 1 Traffic offenses 13 2 5 1 1 3 1 0 0 0 0 Note: Total includes juveniles whose offenses were missing or unclassifiable. *Includes attempted murder. Source: Urban Institute analysis of Federal Bureau of Prisons, SENTRY data base, fiscal years 1999-2008. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201142 Tribal youth served a sentence in federal facilities that was twice as long as the maximum sentence tribal facilities can impose From 1999 to 2008, the average time served by tribal youth tended to be longer (about 26 months, on average) than the tribal justice system maximum sentence of 12 months. The Tribal Law and Order Act of 2010 recently extended the maximum a tribal court can sentence to 3 years for those courts meeting conditions placed on the legal process. The average time served by non-tribal youth in BOP facilities more than doubled from 15 months in 1999 to over 38 months by 2008. Non-tribal youth admitted to the federal prison authorities were somewhat more dispersed than tribal youth with respect to district of commitment About 32% of non-tribal youth were committed from the five federal districts that committed the most tribal youth. Thirty-six percent of non-tribal youth were committed to the BOP from five federal judicial districts along the U.S.-Mexico border: California-Southern, Arizona, New Mexico, Texas-Western, and Texas-Southern. (figure 5.7). Among juveniles admitted to the jurisdiction of the BOP in 2008, non- tribal youth were slightly older at age of offense than tribal youth The average of age tribal youth at time of offense was about 15 years compared to 16 years for non-tribal youth. Most tribal youth were male (92%), American Indian (96%), non- Hispanic (99%), and United States citizens (100%). The majority of non- tribal youth were male (93%), white (60%), non-Hispanic (58%), and United States citizens (71%). 26–6026–60 10–2510–25 1–91–9 00 Number of non-tribal youth admittedNumber of non-tribal youth admitted District of Arizona (19%) New Mexico (5%) District of Western Texas (7%) District of Eastern New York (4%)District of South Dakota (3%) Figure 5.7 Non-tribal youth admitted to the jurisdiction of the Federal Bureau of Prisons, and five federal judicial districts that committed the majority of non-tribal youth, 2006–2008 Source: Based on BJS analysis of data from the Federal Bureau of Prisons, SENTRY database, fiscal years 2006–2008. Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 43 Methodology The primary source of data presented in this report is from the Federal Justice Statistics Program (FJSP). The methodology to identify tribal youth was developed by the Urban Institute, and primary findings reported here are drawn from their 2011 study, Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System (http://ncjrs.gov). This report supplemented findings from the Urban Institute’s study with additional analyses based on BJS analysis of FJSP data. Data from the Federal Bureau of Prisons (BOP), SENTRY database, which contains information on all federally sentenced offenders admitted to BOP jurisdiction at fiscal yearend were analyzed for the years 1994 to 1998. The source of the data in figure 5.1 is The Urban Institute analysis of Executive Office for U.S. Attorneys, National LIONS database, fiscal years 2000 to 2008. Suspects in matters concluded include all matters which were concluded in each respective year. Suspects in matters prosecuted include matters for which the U.S. attorneys in that district made the decision to prosecute the matter in each fiscal year. The unit of count for figure 5.1 is the suspect matter. A matter is a referral on which an attorney spends one hour or more investigating, and on which formal papers have not been filed with the Court. If a decision is made not to continue with the investigation, it is disposed of in the LIONS database by declination and closed. References American Indians and Crime, NCJ 203097, BJS Web, December 2004. 2005 American Indian Population and Labor Force Report. U.S. Department of the Interior, Bureau of Indian Affairs, 2005. The Urban Institute. Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System, NCJ 234549, May 2011. Available at http://ncjrs.gov. Researchers from The Urban Institute investigated how youth from Indian Country were processed by the federal criminal justice system. They used a combination of qualitative and quantitative information, including administrative data from the BJS-sponsored Federal Justice Statistics Program (FJSP) and information drawn from interviews with more than three dozen federal and tribal justice system personnel. Staff at the Urban Institute who contributed to the study included— Co-principal Investigators William Adams and Julie Samuels Contextual Analysis Team Janeen Buck Willison Hannah Dodd Meredith Dank Quantitative Analysis Team Barbara Parthasarathy Kamala Mallik Kane Jessica Kelly Sybil Mendonca KiDeuk Kim Office of Justice Programs Innovation • Partnerships • Safer Neighborhoods http://www.ojp.gov work_aegpcuw3uvfvvak4xwmj7iazo4 ---- Layout 1 HumanitiesCMAJ Partner to the Poor: A Paul Farmer Reader Paul Farmer Haun Saussy, Editor University of California Press; 2010. D r. Paul Farmer is an inspiration. A physician specializing in infectious disease as well as an anthropologist, he was one of the cofounders of Partners In Health in 1987 and has devoted his career to helping the poor gain access to medical services and treatment in Haiti, Rwanda, Peru, Mex- ico, Russia and elsewhere. He is the author of many influential books and essays addressing the impact of what he has termed “structural violence” (the embodiment of poverty and entrenched inequalities as violence) on the health of populations against whom it is directed, as well as a history of Haiti. He was the subject of Tracy Kidder’s bestselling biography Mountains beyond Mountains. Partner to the Poor is a compilation of essays and talks given by Farmer from 1988–2009. They are fascinating, thought-provoking and, despite the fact that some are over 20 years old, relevant to anyone interested in global health and issues related to its disparities. The book’s four sections address the inter- sections of anthropology and medicine at different points: culture, history, ethics, human rights; gender, racial and political inequalities; and access to health care and/or its denial. A prime example of the latter, dis- cussed multiple times throughout the book, is the rapid spread of AIDS in Haiti and Africa during the 1980s and 1990s, and the various approaches sug- gested for halting it. Many opposed sup- plying affordable retroviral medications to some of the hardest hit (and poorest) parts of the world because it was not cost-effective and because of concern that there was insufficient infrastructure in those places to ensure the necessary adherence to prevent the emergence of resistant strains of HIV. Those organiza- tions preferred to focus their efforts on prevention rather than on treatment. Farmer disagreed with this approach, which, in his opinion, ignored the real reasons for the spread of AIDS, namely the socio-economic forces that had led to the collapse of traditional agrarian soci- eties, as well as entrenched poverty and gender inequality, which were all beyond the abilities of any of the organizations to resolve quickly. Farmer and Partners In Health successfully demonstrated that it was possible to achieve real progress in the fight against AIDS when combining prevention with treatment. (Farmer notes that those models that focused only on prevention ultimately proved completely ineffective.) Farmer also argues that properly framing the conversations on how to improve global health and defining their context is critical to understanding the challenges involved in doing so and being able to overcome them. When people defend a reluctance to introduce antiretroviral medication to rural Haiti and Africa because of the cost, he advo- cates using that as the “beginning of a conversation … [rather than] the end of one.” Costs can be brought down, after all, and effectiveness improved. He wonders how one can seriously frame questioning the use of medications not yet approved for use in children by the US Food and Drug Administration to treat multi−drug resistant tuberculosis, which causes 500 000 new cases annu- ally, as an “ethical challenge.” He points out that this is in fact a litigious, not an ethical concern, and that it does not begin to consider the priorities of those so desperately in need of treatment. Similarly, he refers to “the near invisibility of the poor” when describ- ing the reaction to a talk given at Har- vard University by a Rwandan pediatri- cian who was presenting the inroads Partners In Health had made in treating cancer patients in Rwanda. After con- cluding his talk, the pediatrician found himself “upbraided repeatedly about ethical concerns regarding the delivery of cancer care by people not trained in oncology,” despite the fact that there were no oncologists in the Rwandan countryside and that the real alternative was simply to provide no care at all. Farmer concludes one of the essays by writing that “we have no more excuses for ignoring the growing inequality that has left hundreds of mil- lions of people without any hope of surviving preventable and treatable ill- nesses.” This uncompromising commit- ment to social justice, as well as the dedication and steadfast resolve to improve the lives of others are clearly evident throughout the book and his work at large. It is precisely these qual- ities that have made him an inspiration to so many across the world. Dennis Rosen MD Division of Respiratory Diseases Children’s Hospital Boston Harvard Medical School Boston, USA CMAJ • DECEMBER 14, 2010 • 182(18) © 2010 Canadian Medical Association or its licensors E871 Books An uncompromising commitment to social justice D O I: 10 .1 50 3/ cm aj .1 00 82 4 U n iv e rs it y o f C a li fo rn ia P re ss work_aekcwabconag3an3dvhiignvcq ---- Transitional justice and its discontents. This is a repository copy of Transitional justice and its discontents.. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/87535/ Version: Accepted Version Article: McCargo, D (2015) Transitional justice and its discontents. Journal of Democracy, 26 (2). 5 - 20 (16). ISSN 1045-5736 https://doi.org/10.1353/jod.2015.0022 eprints@whiterose.ac.uk https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ Reuse Unless indicated otherwise, fulltext items are protected by copyright with all rights reserved. The copyright exception in section 29 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 allows the making of a single copy solely for the purpose of non-commercial research or private study within the limits of fair dealing. The publisher or other rights-holder may allow further reproduction and re-use of this version - refer to the White Rose Research Online record for this item. Where records identify the publisher as the copyright holder, users can verify any specific terms of use on the publisher’s website. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing eprints@whiterose.ac.uk including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. mailto:eprints@whiterose.ac.uk https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ 1 Transitional Justice and Its Discontents Duncan McCargo Journal of Democracy, April 2015 Duncan McCargo teaches political science at Columbia University and the University of Leeds. His latest book is Mapping National Anxieties: Thailand’s Southern Conflict (2012). He recently completed a Leverhulme Trust Major Research Fellowship on politics and justice. At a military base outside Phnom Penh, two elderly defendants have been refusing since October 2014 to cooperate in the second stage of their trial for presiding over mass killings during the 1975–79 Khmer Rouge regime. A third defendant died in early 2013, a few months after a fourth was ruled unfit to be tried. So far only one case at the Tribunal has run its full course, that of a former torture center chief who is currently serving a life sentence. Cambodia’s authoritarian government (it has long been rated Not Free by Freedom House) is blocking any further arrests, and the US$200 million that the international community has spent so far on a flawed “hybrid” tribunal (it is considered both Cambodian and international) will probably result in just three convictions. Next door in Thailand, the Truth for Reconciliation Commission that was set up to investigate the deaths of 92 people during April and May 2010 demonstrations has failed to offer any strong criticism of the military officers who ordered most of the killings. Instead, the commission has blamed armed elements within protest ranks for precipitating the violence. The Royal Thai Army, its longstanding impunity unchecked, went on to stage yet another coup (Thailand’s twelfth since 1932) in May 2014. Over the past two decades, “transitional justice”—a catch-all phrase that refers both to truth commissions such as the one in Thailand and special courts with criminal-sentencing powers such as the one in Cambodia—has become a vast global industry that employs tens of 2 thousands of people. Kathryn Sikkink lists transitional human-rights prosecutions relating to 48 countries, mainly since the mid-1990s, along with 28 truth commissions.1 Much of the funding for these activities comes via the United Nations, or as donations from Western countries and Japan. In 2014, the UN spent more than $200 million on the Rwandan and former Yugoslavia tribunals alone. Like any such industry, the transitional-justice enterprise has promoters who make optimistic claims about what it is and what it can accomplish.2 Two key milestones mark the rise of transitional justice. The first was the 1995 establishment of South Africa’s postapartheid Truth and Reconciliation Commission (TRC), and the second was the creation in 2002 of the International Criminal Court (ICC), with its headquarters at The Hague. These two institutions have served as oft-imitated models, while the principles and ideals that they are meant to embody have been widely praised and exported. The ICC symbolizes the idea that those responsible for genocide, war crimes, or other crimes against humanity should face trial, not simply in normal domestic courts—which often are too limited in capacity or too politicized to act against political elites or senior security officials—but in specially created international tribunals. By trying these defendants outside ordinary courts and under the highest international standards of justice, such tribunals are meant to exert a potent moral authority that will deter current and future leaders from engaging in terrible criminal acts. These tribunals’ warmest supporters also claim that the principles thus demonstrated can help to improve local judicial systems while also laying some of the groundwork for transitions toward more open and democratic political orders. The South African TRC captured the notion that a transition to democracy must often confront “unfinished business”: histories of human-rights abuses, crimes committed by former regimes, and violent incidents that have gone uninvestigated, sometimes for decades. In many 3 cases, pressing criminal charges against perpetrators (who may also be victims) proves impractical or undesirable. Truth commissions offer a less adversarial means of righting wrongs. Documents and other evidence are collected, witnesses are interviewed, reports are published— but legal immunity is often given, and generally nobody goes to jail. This nonpunitive, quasi- judicial process aims to heal emotional wounds and promote comity between old enemies. The current vogue for transitional justice seems, on its face, eminently reasonable and indeed laudable. Those who have committed atrocities or crimes against humanity deserve to be tried and (if convicted) punished, by an international tribunal if necessary. Societies torn by violence should have a chance to remember, reflect, and pursue reconciliation. The rise of transitional justice has given rise to a huge industry of lawyers, UN staff, NGO activists, consultants, and fellow-traveling academics who are busy setting up tribunals and truth commissions around the world. And always, of course, all is done in close collaboration with local “partners.” A main argument of the industry is that it helps to create “justice cascades” through which norms of fair trials and accountability begin to take hold in national and local contexts. Accountability is an important concept. As Ricardo Blaug argues, it has two core components. The first is scrutiny (who can be made to explain their actions?), and the second is sanction (what consequences will they face?).3 While truth commissions emphasize scrutiny, trials emphasize sanction. Evaluating the success of accountability involves establishing criteria for the effectiveness of transitional-justice initiatives. Much depends on the aims that the mechanisms are meant to serve. These aims may not always be obvious: They could include punishing criminality, asserting morality, creating an “expressive” example, resolving conflicts, aiding political “transitions,” achieving “closure,” enhancing “transparency” and community 4 cohesion, or crafting historical memory. Some of these aims may contradict one another. In some cases, for instance, transitional-justice mechanisms may end up preventing scrutiny—key actors may never testify, commission reports may become exercises in evasion—or they may even obstruct rather than promote the imposition of effective sanctions. Transitional justice, whether brought by tribunal or truth commission, would be great if it worked. Likewise, if its results were unproven but fairly harmless, there would be little to worry about. Money has often been wasted on much worse things. But what if transitional justice all too often proves counterproductive? What if it raises unrealistic hopes, stirs up fears and hatreds, hijacks transition processes, and even strengthens corrupt elites? If the transitional-justice industry spawns new nightmares instead of banishing old ones, then the tribunals and commissions have gone too far. Another oft-heard term in the transitional-justice world is “holistic approach.” The idea is that criminal prosecutions, truth commissions, reparations, gender justice, security-sector reform, and efforts to memorialize victims should often be deployed together. Nevertheless, the syncretism involved in such complementarity is analytically quite confused. Throwing in, for example, promoting more enlightened gender policies and cutting the number of army generals serves to blur the legalistic character of transitional justice—since these are policy measures that can be undertaken by any society. Tribunals on Trial The idea of charging people with crimes against humanity in international courts goes back to the tribunals convened by the victors at the end of the Second World War. As was 5 recognized at the time, it implied no sympathy for the Nazis to point out that the retrospective legal basis on which they were tried was extremely problematic. Radhabinod Pal, the dissenting Indian judge at the Tokyo war-crimes trials (1946–48), condemned that process as a “victor’s charter.”4 Although Pal was moved by his personal hostility to Western imperialism, his closely reasoned dissent became a landmark in international law, making the case for an “even justice”5 grounded in an international “impartial court” with universal jurisdiction. Pal praised moves dating back to a 1920 meeting at The Hague to create an International Court of Criminal Justice, hailing it as a “wise solution to the problem.” By excluding from the dock Allied leaders themselves (who might have been arraigned for the mass bombing of civilians) as well as Emperor Hirohito and his relatives (who were exempted from prosecution by wary occupation authorities), the Tokyo Tribunal proved highly selective in its choice of targets. Telford Taylor, one of the U.S. Nuremberg prosecutors, saw the dangers of selectivity and called upon the United States and other leading nations to create a “permanent international penal jurisdiction” in order to avoid the German perception that Nuremberg “was for Germans only.”6 Does the ICC, which was finally brought into being by the Rome Statute of 2002, fulfill Pal’s hope for “even justice,” or does it continue the Nuremburg tradition of “expressive” trials—procedures legal in form, but with questionable legal bases, that are held for “higher” emotional or moral reasons? And do “expressive” trials not drift perilously close to becoming show trials? Is the ICC supporting international norms and values, or has it come to serve mainly the interests of Western powers? How far is the broader rise of international tribunals, symbolized by the ICC, helping to promote liberal notions of justice? And is there a risk that the proliferation of such tribunals could perversely end up undermining the promotion of justice? 6 Housed at The Hague, the ICC currently has 122 state parties, while a further 31 countries have signed the Rome Statute without ratifying it. A novel feature of the Rome Statute is that the ICC can act without the authorization of the UN Security Council or any particular state; rather, the ICC is deemed to create a parallel form of jurisdiction which is said to “complement” that of the nation-state. To date, the ICC has acted with regard to eight “situations,” opening 21 cases and indicting 36 people. Of those, it has so far convicted just two, while spending a growing budget that in 2009 alone added up to almost $118 million, all of it contributed by the court’s “state parties.” Although preliminary proceedings have begun in cases from Afghanistan, Colombia, Georgia, Honduras, Ukraine, and Venezuela, all those indicted so far have been African, as have been both of those convicted (they are from the Democratic Republic of Congo). This record has caused the African Union to threaten mass withdrawal from the Rome Statute, and to demand that serving heads of state be exempted from ICC indictment while in office. Two major ICC debacles stand out. The first was its ineffectual 2008 indictment of Sudan’s President Omar al-Bashir for crimes against humanity in relation to Darfur. A defiant Bashir retains his post and travels the region with no fear of arrest. The second was the December 2014 decision by the court’s chief prosecutor to drop a case against Kenyan president Uhuru Kenyatta for fomenting 2007 postelection ethnic violence. Kenya, an ICC state party, had covertly sabotaged the investigation.7 The ICC’s limits in dealing with sitting heads of state and ongoing conflicts are painfully clear, and raise the question of how a transitional-justice model can work when there has been no real transition. China, India, Israel, Russia, and the United States are all nonparties to the ICC, and the Arab states (except Jordan) have stayed out as well. The United States, critics charge, prefers 7 special UN-sponsored tribunals, such as those that the Security Council set up to deal with Rwanda and the former Yugoslavia, to the more freewheeling ICC. Although the United States has refused to ratify the Rome Statute, since 2005 it has shifted from an adversarial position and begun working as an ally of the ICC, leading detractors to charge that the court has become “an instrument in the toolkit of major powers responding to instability and violence in weaker states.”8 Thus has an institution founded to pursue impartial justice become a means of managing political problems under the rubric of impartial justice’s moral authority. If this is how the flagship project of “transitional justice” operates, then we might wonder if the adjective—which refers to the political project of promoting certain kinds of regimes over others—outweighs the noun. The ICC’s recent travails underline Victor Peskin’s idea that courtroom trials run parallel with—and may be overshadowed by—“virtual trials,” which are in fact political struggles between the international community and the states where war crimes took place, as well as factional fights within those states. Virtual trials often loom large because international tribunals so frequently represent attempts to lay a scrim of morally superior judicial ritual atop stubborn, messy political realities. Simply put, international tribunals have been created to solve political problems that lie well beyond their capacity to fix. What is needed instead is not more tribunals, but rather more scope for creative political fixes of the sort that legal experts are unlikely ever to generate. Peskin concludes that tribunals (often meaning their chief prosecutors) have sometimes been able to win greater cooperation from targeted states through the use of strategies “ranging from shaming to negotiation.”9 In other words, a tribunal’s ability to deliver justice hinges on how politically skilled its leadership is. If chief prosecutors closet themselves with piles of 8 documents, their courts are likely to fail. Peskin argues that such prosecutors must be good at conciliation and deal-making, even if this risks the appearance of “an exercise that has more to do with politics than with law.”10 In the end, tribunals and truth commissions are quasi-legal processes that have as their goal a stable and fair political settlement. Former International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda legal advisor Kingsley Chiedu Moghala’s extensive research leads him to argue that “using international war crimes trials as a frontline approach to preventing or deterring genocide is a failing policy.”11 Since all supranational transitional justice arrangements are essentially political, they lack the legitimacy to effect real change. Replacing Politics with Legalism In addition to the paucity of evidence that transitional-justice solutions are effective, there is the problem that the entire transitional-justice edifice—whether in its tribunal or its truth- commission form—rests on dubious claims of moral superiority that are used to trump all criticism of transitional justice’s underlying ideological project, which is to replace politics with legalism.12 The matter was set forth most clearly a half-century ago in a seminal book by the political theorist Judith N. Shklar.13 A Harvard academic who as a child fled to North America from her native Latvia in order to escape the Nazis, Shklar was deeply skeptical about the ethical underpinnings of the Nuremburg trials. She became convinced that those who sought to emphasize the priority of justice over politics were quietly subscribing to an ideology—almost always kept implicit—that she called “legalism.” Advocates of legalism liked to insist that the pursuit of justice was somehow suprapolitical and even beyond criticism. Contending that legalism does not stop at merely separating law from politics Shklar charged that legalism looks down on politics 14 9 The divorce of law from politics is, to be sure, designed to prevent arbitrariness, and that is why there is so little argument about its necessity. However, ideologically legalism does not stop there. Politics is regarded as not only something apart from law, but as inferior to law. Law aims at justice, while politics looks only to expediency. The former is neutral and objective, the latter the uncontrolled child of competing interests and ideology. Justice is thus not the policy of legalism, it is treated as a policy superior to and unlike any other.15 Shklar set out to make a countercase for the indispensability of politics. Only by engaging in the give-and-take of sharing and competing for power, she insisted, can a society thrash out its conflicts and disagreements. Political problems need political solutions. Yet once the “crimes against humanity” designation is applied, such solutions are displaced by legalistic steps that invoke the rhetoric of “justice” while failing to solve the irreducibly political problems that troubled societies continue to face. In a 1986 preface to the second edition of her book, Shklar noted that the original edition had “offended virtually all of the lawyers who read it” by treating legalism as a political ideology. Most of them much preferred to assume that legal ideas and institutions are “highly discrete practices” immune from politics. Although the questioning of such assumptions has become more common since Shklar’s time, the problem of regarding law as morally superior to mere politics persists—and is particularly acute in the world of transitional justice. Shklar observed that legalism reveals itself most clearly “at the margins of normality,” as in the Nuremburg and Tokyo tribunals, and noted with some apparent satisfaction: “There have been many wars since then and endless crimes against humanity, but there has been no repetition of the trials that followed the Second World War.”16 Shklar saw Nuremburg as a broadly successful intervention, but largely because the tribunal formed part of a clear and well-crafted political project, and was hence far more than a 10 legalistic exercise. She seemed to view the lack of new international tribunals up to 1986 as betokening a grasp of their shortcomings and hence vindicating her arguments. She died in 1992, before the vogue for transitional justice that came on the heels of the South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission, and would later produce the ICC. What would Shklar have made of this vogue? Her 1986 preface includes an important defense of something she calls “tribunality.” By this, she means that law is an extension of politics, rather than a moral high ground towering somewhere above political life. Tribunality, says Shklar, is “inherent in functioning assemblies, bureaucracies, mediators of all kinds and extends even down to parents as they try to be fair in distributing rewards and penalties’.17 Shklar’s support for the creative legalism found at Nuremburg, which can be justified ‘as an act of legalistic statesmanship and on the basis of its immediate effects on German politics’ (170) offers the lineaments of a blueprint for tribunality: the use of power to promote fairness, which may be done through courts, or through more overtly political institutions. Tribunality is an extension of politics, rather than a moral high ground floating somewhere above the earthly realm; war crimes trials proved worthwhile in the case of the Nazis precisely because of the existing legalistic tradition of German jurisprudence.”18 Law and politics thus form part of what we might term (after Shklar) the “tribunality continuum.” This means that complex political problems can best be addressed by the considered use of tribunality, rather than by merely legalistic solutions. Nuremburg, in her view, showed how tribunality can use power to promote fairness. Yet Shklar warned that international courts can work only in certain cultural and geopolitical circumstances. The Nazi war-crimes trials proved worthwhile precisely because of the existing tradition of German jurisprudence. The Tokyo trials, by contrast, “achieved nothing 11 whatever.” In short, “one could justify the Nuremburg trials only on political grounds, and the Tokyo ones not at all.”19 While the U.S. occupation of Japan achieved much success despite the Tokyo tribunals’ failure, this success was not juridical. It was political. A defeated aggressor was brought back into the family of nations, with new-minted or remodeled institutions that remain largely unchanged seven decades later. The Constitution of 1947, written by General Douglas MacArthur’s staff, has yet to be amended. In large measure, the enduring character of the occupation-era reforms reflects the Japanese people’s sense that they are relatively fair. The transitional-justice industry does not, as a rule, pay much attention to the messy particularities of history. Instead, it seeks to generalize an approach that is only likely to work under tightly circumscribed conditions. Moral grounds, never political ones, are used to justify all transitional-justice interventions. What should be done in cases such as Cambodia or Rwanda, where tens of thousands of perpetrators may have killed hundreds of thousands of victims? Are criminal proceedings a useful response to such terrible events? Would convicting some perpetrators amount to a form of justice? Does such justice serve the purposes of “transition”? Does it support moves toward a more open and liberal-democratic political order? The logical conclusion from Shklar’s analysis is that the world needs less transitional justice, and more use of judicious tribunality. In order to right wrongs, to punish the cruel, and to secure some tentative gains for liberalism—albeit Shklar’s ever-watchful “liberalism of fear”— real politics and not some putatively suprapolitical legalism must openly take center-stage. As the case of Cambodia illustrates, the notion of transitional justice is based on an implicit moral hierarchy, with “justice” at the top, politics below, and security measures at the bottom. 12 This might be summarized as “Justice: Try Khmer Rouge leaders. Politics: Craft a democratic polity. Security: Remove Khmer Rouge from power.” Note that the last item on the list must be the first to happen on the ground. The Khmer Rouge were toppled from power in January 1979, but this has not become an action imbued with much prestige or importance. That is mostly because it was carried out by the army of communist Vietnam, an adversary of the United States and the pro-Western regional grouping, ASEAN. The recrafting of the Cambodian polity by the UN Transitional Authority in Cambodia (or UNTAC, 1992–93), based upon a long process of peace talks, has by contrast been seen as an important moral mission of the international community and a prototype for UN-brokered political transitions since. Yet simply installing some form of elected government in Cambodia was insufficient to complete this moral project: At least partly because of Western guilt at having failed to act against the murderous Khmer Rouge regime in the 1970s, there were persistent demands for an international tribunal to prosecute its leading figures. I am not suggesting that those responsible for mass murder should go unpunished, but only noting that the pressing of criminal charges in such a situation will inevitably run into moral, political, and practical problems. Up to two-million people were killed in Cambodia between April 1975 and January 1979– almost a quarter of the country’s population.20 The number of perpetrators was huge as well, and some perpetrators had become victims. The first trial was that of Khaing Guek Eav (better known as Duch), the commandant of the S-21 detention and interrogation center. This former school became the place where Khmer Rouge cadres were locked up once the paranoid movement began to turn on its own. Many of the thousands who were held in unspeakable conditions, tortured, and executed at S-21 had themselves taken part in the torture or execution of others. Indeed, many guards at S-21 met the 13 same fate as those whom they had interrogated. The distinction between victims and perpetrators was not just blurred, it was often nonexistent. Much of the motivation for the Khmer Rouge tribunal is political. There is collective international regret that UNTAC came and went without loosening the authoritarian grip of Prime Minister Hun Sen and his Cambodian People’s Party (CPP), which has been in power since 1979. The tribunal represents an implicit attempt to destabilize Hun Sen and promote regime change, in keeping with the longstanding Western desire for a “noncommunist opposition” that can transform Cambodia for the better.21 The problem with this game is that two can play. While donors to the Extraordinary Chambers in the Courts of Cambodia (ECCC) may privately hope to delegitimize Hun Sen by taking on Cambodia’s “culture of impunity,” the premier and his aides skillfully point to the trials to highlight their own pet themes. They love to dwell on how their government freed Cambodians from the killing fields, and has since rebuilt the country “from scratch.” If the source of Cambodia’s problems lies in the Khmer Rouge past, they are in effect saying, then the solution to them lies with Hun Sen and the CPP. If, as looks extremely probable, Hun Sen’s government will be able to bar any suspects beyond the original five from being indicted, then liberal ideals of global justice will have taken a hard hit. The Khmer Rouge tribunal may then stand exposed as a high-water mark, showing where the real-world effectiveness (if not the lingering popularity) of the transitional-justice trend began to recede. Some of the tribunal’s problems have been procedural and technical, but the basic shortcoming has been the inability of the UN and major donors such as Japan, Australia, the United States and Germany to resist the CPP regime’s endless game-playing. In truth, a fully Cambodian court with UN technical support would have been a more viable option – albeit more transparently under Hun Sen’s control .22 The ECCC has been termed a ‘black 14 sheep’ among UN-backed tribunals,23 but that does not let “hybrid” justice off the hook: The problems of the Cambodian case, like others at the “margins of normality,” are simply more visible than those elsewhere. Prosecuting Heads of State Take the more straightforward case of an elected leader who apparently abuses her authority. In an electoral democracy, should the voters decide her fate at the next ballot? Or should she face impeachment and formal removal from office by a constitutional, political process? Or street protests and demands for resignation? Or should she be hauled up on domestic criminal charges, and possibly sentenced to jail? In the twenty-first century, recourse to judicial measures to address all manner of abuses of power has become a kneejerk reaction, one which testifies to the inexorable rise of legalism. Ellen Lutz and Caitlin Reiger cite Shklar’s criticism of political trials as legal proceedings in which powerful actors seek to eliminate their political enemies, but then argue that such cases are now in the minority.24 They distinguish, in effect, between “bad” political trials, in which politics gains the upper hand over justice, and “good” political trials, which reflect a desire for public accountability. But the distinction may not always be so clear. But the distinction is not as straightforward as this narrative suggests. Lutz takes as her starting point a campaign to pursue former Philippine dictator Ferdinand Marcos through the courts on corruption charges. Yet parallel campaigns to indict another Philippine president, Joseph Estrada, were hijacked by his political opponents: In countries where corruption is ubiquitous, just about anyone who has ever held public office can be hit with corruption charges. Under such conditions, too much legalism may bring not greater order, but deadlock or even chaos. However superficially attractive it may seem, criminalizing political leaders for their bad behavior or questionable decisions risks devaluing or undermining the political process. This tendency has assumed an extreme form in Thailand, where no fewer than three prime ministers 15 were judicially ousted between 2008 and 2014, spawning strife, instability, and a military coup. Samak Sundaravej, was thrown out in 2008 on a technicality for having hosted a televised cooking show—an example of legalism gone mad. There are times when invoking judicial mechanisms in order to bring down a controversial figure or resolve a political contention may backfire and rouse rather than settle passions. Truth Commissions Although the transitional-justice industry is best known for the ICC and other criminal tribunals, the exponential growth of truth commissions has been a parallel development over the past two decades. A classic truth commission belongs to the time after a transition away from authoritarianism has occurred, when a more open political order is being built. The task is to investigate (but not prosecute) the misdeeds of the old, unfree regime. Truth commissions typically seek to make an accurate public record of the past, to give victims some sense of acknowledgment and “closure,” to “name and shame” (but not jail or fine) perpetrators, to promote society-wide reflection and reconciliation, and to suggest partial remedies such as reparations for documented victims.25 In some cases, truth commissions are a second-best recourse for those cases where there are too many perpetrators to try, or where putting former regime officials in the dock might be too explosive. But increasingly, such commissions are promoted as morally desirable projects in their own right, unrelated to questions of criminal prosecution. Much as the shadow of Nuremburg looms over the ICC and other hybrid courts, the South African TRC is the model for truth commissions. It had various quasi-judicial features 16 including extensive witness hearings, and it was empowered to issue amnesties. Most of the scholarly attention paid to truth commissions has gone to what Patricia Hayner terms “strong” versions of them (her use of “strong” versus “weak,” we should note, allows her to avoid harder discussions about “successful” versus “failed”). In the strong category she places not only the South African TRC, but commissions in Guatemala, Morocco, Peru, and Timor Leste.26 Strong commissions typically combine a potent sense of purpose with extensive public engagement, and come up with well-crafted recommendations that are broadly well-received. Hayner has offered a checklist of desirable features for strong commissions, including a wide mandate, investigative powers, a term of two to three years, a sizeable budget, and a staff numbering at least a hundred people.27 Other assets for commissions include a sharply defined time period to examine, considerable public buy-in, sympathetic media coverage, strong domestic and international political support, and lack of national-government interference. Of the more than forty truth commissions that have been created to date, only a small share have met Hayner’s technical criteria for strength. But we need to work with a much broader set of accountability criteria: To what extent did these commissions bring about genuine forms of scrutiny? How far did they lay the groundwork for appropriate sanctions? Most commissions are flawed, many are weak, and some border on outright dysfunction. The prospect of finding fault with an enterprise that holds up as its guiding ideals such universally praised concepts as justice, truth, and reconciliation does not appear to be an appetizing one in many eyes. Hence the stealthy mushrooming of second- and third-rate truth commissions has drawn remarkably little critical scrutiny. For the sake of argument, let us assume (even if we doubt this to be the case) that the rare “strong” commissions are relatively unproblematic. We must still ask: Is there any evidence that 17 weak commissions do any good? Could some of them actually prove harmful, by stirring up dark memories, exacerbating conflicts, destabilizing regimes, or even generating fresh rounds of violence? In short, can one say that any truth commission is always better than no truth commission? A brief discussion of two failed Thai inquiries may help to illustrate some of the problems faced by truth commissions. In 2005, the Thai government established a National Reconciliation Commission (NRC) to examine the resurgence of separatist violence in the country’s Muslim-majority southern provinces. It was chaired by distinguished former prime minister Anand Panyarachun.28 After commissioning an impressive series of research projects, the NRC put out in mid-2006 a 132-page final report that contained many airy references to justice, but no serious discussion of either the perpetrators of violence or the underlying questions of governance and representation facing the country. This anodyne document swiftly sank without a trace while the premier who had commissioned it, Thaksin Shinawatra, was ousted in a September 2006 military coup. In the 2011 edition of her standard book on truth commissions, Hayner does not even mention the NRC. Like many such bodies, Thailand’s NRC was not intended simply to promote truth or reconciliation. Rather, it was a political project initially designed to deflect attention from Thaksin’s botched handling of the southern conflict. Soon enough, however, the commission’s proceedings became a focus for opposition to the Thaksin government led by a group of liberal royalists, and so helped create the conditions for the coup. The southern conflict was not a transitional-justice problem; it was a political problem, in need of a political solution. Much the same was true of the Thai Truth for Reconciliation Commission mentioned at the outset of this essay. By far the greatest number of those killed in the 2010 violence had been 18 pro-Thaksin civilian protestors shot by the military, but the commission’s report blamed mainly the demonstrators.29 Leading commission members were known allies of the anti-Thaksin movement, and their report studiously avoided talking about the longstanding policy of impunity for state officials that allows the Royal Thai Army to be so free in its use of force. This unwillingness to criticize the military helped to create the conditions for yet another coup, this time in May 2014. As window-dressing, the commission even invited Hayner and other transitional-justice luminaries to visit Bangkok. The commission deployed the rhetoric of transitional justice despite a patent lack of the powers, resources, or political support that a strong truth commission requires. These two Thai cases illustrate a disturbing trend: the rise of half-baked truth commissions that “talk the talk” of transitional justice to disguise serious shortcomings. For more than a century, commissions of inquiry have investigated matters of grave public concern without overdoing claims regarding justice and truth. Outstanding examples in the English- speaking world include the two inquiries into the sinking of the Titanic, the Warren Commission, and the Franks Commission on the Falklands War. All had their shortcomings, but at least none came cloaked in the specious moralism of many recent transitional-justice exercises. For the most part, we need more (and better) public inquiries, and fewer truth commissions. Transitional Justice and History In Postwar, his magisterial survey of Europe since 1945, Tony Judt argues that institutional efforts to expose past injustices (such as the construction of Holocaust memorials and museums) proved less important than the fostering of regular historical inquiry. Such history can contribute to disenchantment and disruption, and as Judt warned, “it is not always politically 19 prudent to wield the past as a moral cudgel with which to beat and berate a people for its past sins.” Yet even bearing this in mind, he still believed that the historian’s “rigorous investigation and interrogation” of the past remained of central importance.30 The relationship between transitional justice and history is a complex one. The Khmer Rouge tribunal, for example, cannot function without research and evidence provided by professional historians. Yet international tribunals are concerned with securing legal outcomes and not with exploring messy historical debates. As such, they may easily become moral cudgels of exactly the kind that Judt warns against. Catalyzing public discussion about the Khmer Rouge period was arguably one of the Cambodia tribunal’s greatest contributions, but was “only tangentially related to its mandate.”31 Would funding and disseminating high-quality historical studies of the Khmer Rouge era have accomplished more than holding trials? The 1983–84 Argentinian National Commission on Disappeared People (CONADEP), which pre-dated the South African TRC, was too much like a classic presidential commission of “the great and the good” to satisfy most transitional-justice specialists. Yet in under a year CONADEP produced the Nunca Más (Never Again) report, which became a best-seller and has shaped subsequent historical memories and understandings of the thousands of “disappearances” and other rights violations committed by the military dictatorship that ruled Argentina from 1976 to 1983. CONADEP’s successes were based on strong political will and widespread popular support, while Nunca Más was crafted by Commission president Ernesto Sabato, a brilliant novelist, who included poignant verbatim quotations from witness statements on virtually every page.32 The recent flounderings of the ICC, the manifest shortcomings of the Khmer Rouge tribunal and other ad hoc international or hybrid courts, the proliferation of mixed-quality truth 20 commissions—all illustrate the failures of global legalism and undermine the claims to moral superiority that underpin the transitional-justice industry. It is time to curb our well-intentioned celebratory impulses and recognize that, just as earlier waves of democratic transitions are now faltering, so has transitional justice passed its peak. Redressing matters will involve acknowledging that transitional justice is ultimately politics in the guise of legalism, and that the problems of postconflict and posttransition societies are essentially political ones. It is time to desist from the impulse to laud every transitional- justice initiative and instead carefully assess what seems viable, realistic, and unlikely to do further harm . Law does not exist on a higher moral plane above politics, but is simply part of a continuum of solutions. Let us instead dust off Shklar’s too-long-neglected idea that representative assemblies (including parliamentary committees) or even benevolent bureaucracies can perform much of the work that transitional justice assigns to trial chambers and truth commissions: justice can best be achieved through the appropriate use of political power to promote fairness, what Shklar terms tribunality Solutions to complex political problems need to be more creative, sometimes deploying legal mechanisms, but never in purely legalistic ways. By and large, the international community should get out of the business of putting people on trial. Let fact-finding go forward, by all means, but do not lard it with overreaching talk of “truth and reconciliation.” Above all, we need good historical research into deadly conflicts, in accessible formats, widely disseminated and debated in the very places where the violence has taken place. The goals of accounting for the past and of preventing future mass violence are shared by all: the only question is how best to pursue these noble ideas. NOTES 21 The author gratefully acknowledges funding for this project from a Leverhulme Trust Major Research Fellowship, 2011–14, F00 122BC. He also thanks Ricardo Blaug for his invaluable comments. 1 Kathryn Sikkink, The Justice Cascade (New York: Norton, 2011), 266–70. Sikkink’s figure for the number of truth commissions is rather conservative; Hayner names forty (pp. 256-64), and even her list is arguably not complete. 2 See, for example, Kathryn Sikkink’s claims that “a world without any accountability for major episodes of human rights violations is receding,” Justice Cascade, 262; or Geoffrey Robertson’s assertion that “war crimes jurisprudence has an epic quality which is beginning to be to be cited in national courts around the world,” in his Crimes Against Humanity: The Struggle for Global Justice (New York: New Press, 2006), xxxii. 3 See Ricardo Blaug, “Direct Accountability at the End” in Stuart White and Daniel Leighton, Building a Citizen Society: The Politics of Republican Democracy (London: Lawrence and Wishart, 2008), 101–11. 4 Radhabinod Pal, Crimes in International Relations (Calcutta: University of Calcutta, 1955), 195–229 and 403. 5 Timothy Brook , “The Tokyo Judgment and the Rape of Nanking,” Journal of Asian Studies 60 (2001): 696. 6 Telford Taylor, Final Report to the Secretary of the Army on the Nuernberg War Crimes Trials under Control Council Law No. 10, (Washington DC: US Government Printing Office, 1949), 112. 7 For a discussion see Karen J. Alter, “The Trials and Tribulations of Prosecuting Heads of States: Kenyatta and the ICC,” www.washingtonpost.com/blogs/monkey-cage/wp/2014/12/19/the-trials-and- tribulations-of-prosecuting-heads-of-states-kenyatta-and-the-icc. 8 David Bosco, Rough Justice: The International Criminal Court in a World of Power Politics (New York: Oxford University Press 2014), 187. 9 Victor Peskin, International Justice in Rwanda and the Balkans: Virtual Trials and the Struggle for State Cooperation (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2008), 236–37. 10 Peskin, International Justice, 243. 11 Kingsley Chiedu Moghala, Global Justice: The Politics of War Crimes Trials, (Stanford CA: Stanford University Press, 2008), 178. 12 These are closely linked to what Kent terms the “celebratory impulse.” See Lia Kent, The Dynamics of Transitional Justice: International Models and Local Realities in East Timor (Abingdon: Routledge 2012), 205–6. 13 Judith N. Shklar, Legalism: Law, Morals, and Political Trials (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1964; 2nd ed. with new preface, 1986). http://leeds.summon.serialssolutions.com/2.0.0/link/0/eLvHCXMwY2AwNtIz0EUrE9LMUtJSTFPT0oyBHWijNAPzVHPQfXaJFgZGycACEbSVONjHJMTJJCjMNIgHUZ65CTEwpeaJMji4uYY4e-giNiPEF0AOY4gHHY9cWJqfEg_sXsaXggbo4oFldLyvZ6iBYTz4-BEzYBfJWIyBBdidTpVgUDBONjc2MjROSjW2BLVWkixSU82A7XLQITbmpknmlpIMlmRbAwDs00jE http://leeds.summon.serialssolutions.com/2.0.0/link/0/eLvHCXMwY2AwNtIz0EUrE9LMUtJSTFPT0oyBHWijNAPzVHPQfXaJFgZGycACEbSVONjHJMTJJCjMNIgHUZ65CTEwpeaJMji4uYY4e-giNiPEF0AOY4gHHY9cWJqfEg_sXsaXggbo4oFldLyvZ6iBYTz4-BEzYBfJWIyBBdidTpVgUDBONjc2MjROSjW2BLVWkixSU82A7XLQITbmpknmlpIMlmRbAwDs00jE 22 14 Shklar, Legalism, 111. 15 Judith N. Shklar, Legalism (Cambridge MA: Harvard 1964), 111 (second edition with new preface, Harvard 1986). 16 Shklar, Legalism, 1986, xiii. 17 Shklar, Legalism,1986, viii–xi 18 Shklar, Legalism, viii–xi 19 Cited in Andreas Hess, The Political Theory of Judith N. Shklar, Exile from Exile (New York: Palgrave-Macmillan, 2014), 69. 20 For a detailed discussion of this contentious question, see Bruce Sharp, “Counting Hell”, 2008, www.mekong.net/cambodia/deaths.htm. 21 See John D. Ciorciari, “History and Politics Behind the Khmer Rouge Trials,” in John D. Ciorciari and Anne Heindel, eds., On Trial: The Khmer Rouge Accountability Process (Phnom Penh: DC-CAM, 2009), 20–21; and the discussion in Duncan McCargo, “Politics by Other Means? The Virtual Trials of the Khmer Rouge Tribunal,” International Affairs 87 (2011): 613–27. 22 For an argument along these lines, see John D. Ciorciari and Anne Heindel, Hybrid Justice, The Extraordinary Chambers in the Courts of Cambodia (Ann Arbor MI: University of Michigan Press, 2014), 274–77. 23 Ciorciari and Heindel, Hybrid Justice, 10. 24 Ellen L. Lutz, and Caitlin Reiger, “Introduction” in Ellen L. Lutz and Caitlin Reiger, eds., Prosecuting Heads of State (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2009), 10-11. 25 See Ernesto Verdeja, Unchopping a Tree: Reconciliation in the Aftermath of Political Violence (Philadelphia: Temple University Press 2009), 112–13. 26 Patricia Hayner, Unspeakable Truths: Transitional Justice and the Challenge of Truth Commissions (New York: Routledge, 2011) 27–44. 27 Hayner, Unspeakable Truths, 285–86. 28 See Duncan McCargo, “Thailand’s National Reconciliation Commission: A Flawed Response to the Southern Conflict,” Global Change, Peace and Security 22 (February 2010): 75–91. 29 Duncan McCargo and Naruemon Thabchumpon, “Wreck/Conciliation: The Politics of Truth Commissions in Thailand,” Journal of East Asian Studies 14 (2014): 377–404. 30 Tony Judt, Postwar: A History of Europe Since 1945 (New York: Penguin, 2005), 830. 31 Ciorciari and Heindel, Hybrid Justice, 258. 32 The whole book may be read online at www.desaparecidos.org/nuncamas/web/english/library/nevagain/nevagain_000.htm. For an excellent 23 discussion, see Emilio Crenzel, Memory of the Argentina Disappearances: The Political History of Nunca Más (New York: Routledge 2012). work_afkq2zf2mfdfba4banuelymesi ---- eap1200011a Okasha, S. (2012). Social justice, genomic justice, and the veil of ignorance: Harsanyi meets Mendel. Economics and Philosophy, 28(1), 43-71. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0266267112000119 Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Link to published version (if available): 10.1017/S0266267112000119 Link to publication record in Explore Bristol Research PDF-document Copyright Cambridge University Press. University of Bristol - Explore Bristol Research General rights This document is made available in accordance with publisher policies. Please cite only the published version using the reference above. Full terms of use are available: http://www.bristol.ac.uk/red/research-policy/pure/user-guides/ebr-terms/ https://doi.org/10.1017/S0266267112000119 https://doi.org/10.1017/S0266267112000119 https://research-information.bris.ac.uk/en/publications/170a0970-2b62-4e96-bc1b-b23c3760fe88 https://research-information.bris.ac.uk/en/publications/170a0970-2b62-4e96-bc1b-b23c3760fe88 Economics and Philosophy, 28 (2012) 43–71 Copyright C© Cambridge University Press doi:10.1017/S0266267112000119 SOCIAL JUSTICE, GENOMIC JUSTICE AND THE VEIL OF IGNORANCE: HARSANYI MEETS MENDEL SAMIR OKASHA University of Bristol, UK samir.okasha@bristol.ac.uk John Harsanyi and John Rawls both used the veil of ignorance thought experiment to study the problem of choosing between alternative social arrangements. With his ‘impartial observer theorem’, Harsanyi tried to show that the veil of ignorance argument leads inevitably to utilitarianism, an argument criticized by Sen, Weymark and others. A quite different use of the veil-of-ignorance concept is found in evolutionary biology. In the cell- division process called meiosis, in which sexually reproducing organisms produce gametes, the chromosome number is halved; when meiosis is fair, each gene has only a fifty percent chance of making it into any gamete. This creates a Mendelian veil of ignorance, which has the effect of aligning the interests of all the genes in an organism. This paper shows how Harsanyi’s version of the veil-of-ignorance argument can shed light on Mendelian genetics. There turns out to be an intriguing biological analogue of the impartial observer theorem that is immune from the Sen/Weymark objections to Harsanyi’s original. 1. INTRODUCTION In A Theory of Justice, Rawls (1971) invoked the device of an ‘original position’ to study the problem of social justice. He imagined someone Acknowledgements: Thanks to Ken Binmore, Cedric Paternotte, Jonathan Grose, Ellen Clarke and Johannes Martens for discussion. Thanks to an anonymous referee for Economics and Philosophy, and to the editor, for detailed comments. Thanks also to audiences at Oxford, Vienna and Bristol where versions of this material were presented. Financial support from the UK Arts and Humanities Research Council and from the European Research Council is gratefully acknowledged. 43 44 SAMIR OKASHA forced to choose between alternative social arrangements from behind a ‘veil of ignorance’, i.e. without knowing which member of society she will become. Rawls maintained, controversially, that the rational agent would choose the social alternative which maximized the prospects of the least well-off member of society - the maximin principle. As is well known, Rawls was not the first to use a veil of ignorance argument to think about social justice. In two famous papers, Harsanyi (1953, 1955) imagined a ‘sympathetic, impartial observer’, again tasked with choosing between social alternatives from behind a veil; a still earlier version of the idea was sketched by Vickrey (1945). By contrast with Rawls, Harsanyi argued that the veil-of-ignorance thought experiment leads inevitably to utilitarianism, an argument that has come to be called the ‘impartial observer theorem’. Harsanyi arrived at this conclusion by assuming that the impartial observer has an equal chance of becoming any individual, and chooses between social alternatives in accordance with expected utility maximization. Most recent commentators regard Harsanyi’s treatment of the veil of ignorance as superior to Rawls, given Rawls’s largely unmotivated rejection of orthodox decision theory. But even so, controversy surrounds the impartial observer theorem. A number of authors, notably Sen (1976, 1977, 1986), Weymark (1991), Roemer (1998) and Mongin (2001), have argued that Harsanyi’s theorem does not constitute a good argument for classical utilitarianism, for reasons explained below. There is a large and well-known literature on this issue. What is much less well-known is that the veil-of-ignorance concept has also surfaced in evolutionary biology, in a context quite remote from the traditional Rawls/Harsanyi debate. During meiosis – the cell- division process by which sexually reproducing organisms make gametes – the chromosome number is halved: only one of each chromosome pair is passed to each gamete. Most of the time meiosis is ‘fair’, so that any particular gene has a 50% chance of making it into any gamete – a fact known as Mendel’s law of segregation. The law has profound evolutionary consequences, as it equalizes the interests of all the genes in the organism, ensuring they work for the common good; see section 5. Indeed fair meiosis, or Mendelian segregation, is arguably a prerequisite for the very existence of cohesive organisms such as ourselves. That fair meiosis serves to equalize genes’ interests was first emphasized by Leigh (1971), and is now an accepted biological principle. But it is only recently that the intriguing analogy between fair meiosis and the veil of ignorance has come to light. In both, randomization is used to deprive self-interested agents (genes and individuals) of information about their identity, forcing them to adopt an impartial perspective. This analogy is noted in passing by the biologists Haig and Bergstrom (1995) and Frank (2003), who cite both Rawls and Harsanyi, but the only SOCIAL JUSTICE, GENOMIC JUSTICE AND THE VEIL OF IGNORANCE 45 extended discussion of which I am aware is in a semi-popular book by Mark Ridley (2000), who mentions only Rawls.1 The aim of this paper is to consider in detail whether the traditional veil-of-ignorance concept can be used to understand Mendelian genetics. Can the Harsanyi/Rawls thought experiment shed light on the actual process of fair meiosis? I suggest that it can, and in particular that there is an interesting biological analogue of the impartial observer theorem. This may sound like a rather unlikely project, so it is worth briefly explaining the motivation for it, which is three-fold. Firstly, there are many interesting parallels between economics and evolutionary biology, arising because the concept of utility in the former plays a similar role to the concept of fitness in the latter. The importing of game-theoretic concepts into biology is the best known illustration of this role-isomorphism, but is not the only one. The current project also trades on the utility/fitness connection, and is in part an attempt to better understand the elusive relation between these two concepts. Secondly, there is plenty still to say about how the veil-of-ignorance idea applies to genetics. Ridley’s discussion, though illuminating, is compromised by his considering only Rawls’s version of the veil of ignorance. Since Harsanyi arguably had the more coherent version, his is the better place to look for a link with Mendelian genetics. Additionally, Ridley’s treatment contains a subtle confusion between proximate and ultimate explanations, as I argue below, and ends up locating the link in the wrong place. Thirdly, my project fits naturally with a philosophically exciting way of thinking about Darwinian evolution, which treats genes as if they were rational agents trying to maximize a utility function. This approach, aptly dubbed the ‘heuristic of personification’ by Sober (1998), permeates mod- ern evolutionary thinking and is of undoubted value for some purposes. But doubts over its legitimacy have often been raised.2 By modelling genes as individuals behind a veil of ignorance, I hope to illustrate both the power and the limitations of the personification heuristic. The structure of this paper is as follows. Section 2 expounds Harsanyi’s version of the veil-of-ignorance argument. Section 3 outlines the now-standard objections to the argument due to Sen (1986) and 1 Skyrms (1996) discusses what he calls the ‘Darwinian veil of ignorance’ in his work on the evolution of the social contract, but his use of this notion is unrelated to the one explored here, as it has nothing in particular to do with Mendelian genetics. The same is true of Binmore’s (2006) attempt to locate the Rawls/Harsanyi ‘original position’ in an evolutionary context. 2 Personifying genes as an aid to evolutionary reasoning was employed extensively by Dawkins in The Selfish Gene (1976), though the roots of the idea are found in W.D. Hamilton’s papers from the 1960s (1964). Haig (1997) presents a sophisticated defence of the heuristic, and Godfrey-Smith (2009) a sophisticated critique. 46 SAMIR OKASHA Weymark (1991). Section 4 provides some biological background on Mendelian genetics. Section 5 considers the evolutionary function of fair meiosis, and its implications. Section 6 explores two different ways of modelling fair meiosis in Harsanyi’s framework. Section 7 examines paral- lels, conceptual and formal, between Harsanyi’s impartial observer argu- ment and our evolutionary analogue. It is argued that the Sen/Weymark critique of Harsanyi’s argument does not apply to the evolutionary ana- logue. Section 8 compares my analysis with Ridley’s. Section 9 concludes. 2. HARSANYI’S IMPARTIAL OBSERVER ARGUMENT Harsanyi’s own formulation of the impartial observer argument is rather elliptical, so I draw on the careful reconstructions by Weymark (1991) and Mongin (2001). The context is a standard social choice setting. There is a finite set of social alternatives S, which could for example be alternative distributions of resources among society’s members. There is a finite set of individuals I . Each individual has a (weak) preference order over the alternatives in S. The preference order of the i th individual will be denoted Ri ; so ‘x Ri y’ means that the i th individual weakly prefers social alternative x to y. Harsanyi assumes further that each individual has a preference order over the set of lotteries whose prizes are the members of S, i.e. the set of probability distributions over S, denoted �S. These lotteries will be called simple lotteries (to be contrasted with the extended lotteries below). Thus for example if S = {x, y, z} then one simple lottery is < P (x) = 14 , P (y) = 1 2 , P (z) = 14 >. Obviously, any alternative x in S can be identified with the simple lottery that gives x probability 1 of occurring. The point of consid- ering preferences over lotteries is to license the introduction of cardinal utility. Each individual’s preferences over �S are assumed to satisfy the von Neumann–Morgenstern (vNM) axioms, hence can be represented by an expectational utility function unique up to affine transformation. Harsanyi then imagines a hypothetical ‘impartial observer’ who is sympathetic to the interests of the members of society, and is able to imagine himself in the role of any member. The observer can evaluate ‘extended alternatives’ of the form ‘being individual 2 in social alternative x’. An extended alternative is thus an ordered pair of an individual and a social alternative; the set of all extended alternatives is I × S. The observer is assumed to have a preference order over this set; thus he can make judgements such as ‘I would prefer to be individual 2 in alternative x than individual 3 in alternative y’. Harsanyi next considers the set of lotteries over the extended alterna- tives, or the ‘extended lotteries’3, denoted �(I × S). He assumes that the 3 This terminology comes from Weymark (1991). SOCIAL JUSTICE, GENOMIC JUSTICE AND THE VEIL OF IGNORANCE 47 impartial observer has a preference order over the extended lotteries that satisfies the expected utility axioms, so is representable by a vNM utility function. We let Ro denote the observer’s preference order over �(I × S), and let uo denote a particular vNM utility representation of Ro . One subset of the extended lotteries is of particular significance: the impartial extended lotteries in which the observer has an equal chance of becoming any member of society.4 Thus if there are n individuals in set I , the lottery < P (x, i ) = 1n for all i > is the impartial extended lottery in which social alternative x definitely occurs and the observer has an equal chance of becoming any individual. (The corresponding simple lottery is < P (x) = 1 >, i.e. alternative x for certain.) Harsanyi assumes that the probability that the observer becomes any given individual is independent of the probability that any particular social alternative occurs. This means that for every simple lottery there is a unique impartial extended lottery that corresponds to it, i.e. which yields the same marginal probabilities for the social alternatives as the simple lottery. A simple example may help illustrate. Suppose there are two social alternatives x and y, and two individuals. So S = {x, y}, and I = {1, 2}. There are four extended alternatives: {(1, x), (1, y), (2, x), (2, y)}. Consider the simple lottery L 1 in which x occurs with probability 2/3 and y with 1/3, i.e. L 1 = < P (x) = 23 , P (y) = 13 >. The impartial extended lottery E1 that corresponds to L 1 is then: < P (1, x) = 13 , P (1, y) = 16 , P (2, x) = 1 3 , P (2, y) = 16 >. Note that E1 gives the observer equal chances of becoming either person, and gives alternatives x and y the same probability of occurrence as does L 1. Also, E1 makes the probability that the observer is a given person independent of the probability that a given social alternative occurs. Since the impartial observer is sympathetic to the interests of society’s members, Harsanyi proposes a link between the preferences of the observer when he is imagining himself to be a given individual, and the preferences of that individual himself. The observer’s ordering of extended lotteries in which he is definitely individual i should coincide with individual i ’s ordering of the corresponding simple lotteries. This is Harsanyi’s principle of acceptance. The underlying idea is that each individual’s personal preferences are sovereign, so when the observer imagines himself in the shoes of a given individual he thereby imagines himself to have that individual’s personal preferences. From the observer’s preference ordering over the impartial extended lotteries, Harsanyi then derives a social preference over the simple lotteries, and thus over the social alternatives themselves. He simply 4 Giving the observer an equal chance of becoming any individual is Harsanyi’s way of modelling the observer’s epistemic position from behind the veil of ignorance. Harsanyi is invoking the classical principle of indifference at this juncture, as Mongin (2001) notes. 48 SAMIR OKASHA postulates that society’s preference between simple lotteries derives from the observer’s preference between the corresponding impartial extended lotteries. Consider two simple lotteries L 1 and L 2 and the corresponding impartial lotteries E1 and E2. Harsanyi says that L 1 is socially preferable to L 2 if and only if the impartial observer would prefer E1 to E2. Since any social alternative is itself a (degenerate) simple lottery, this yields a way of ordering the social alternatives. Clearly, Harsanyi’s extraction of a social preference from the observer’s extended preferences rests on an ethical judgement. Harsanyi thinks that society should choose between alternatives (or lotteries) according to how a sympathetic observer, with an equal chance of becoming any individual, would choose between them. Intuitively this captures our concept of social justice quite well, but its ethical standing could obviously be questioned. The ingredients are now in place for Harsanyi to derive his utilitarian conclusion. Suppose R is the social preference order on the simple lotteries, defined via the observer’s extended preference order Ro . Since Ro satisfies the vNM axioms, so does R. Thus R can be represented by a vNM utility function u, which we may call the ‘social utility function’. Harsanyi then shows that the social utility function can be expressed as the average of all the individual’s utility functions. So society follows an average utilitarian rule: it ranks simple lotteries (and thus alternatives) according to the average utility that they bring to members of society. This is the impartial observer theorem. More precisely, what Harsanyi shows is this. There exist individual vNM utility functions u1, ..., un, one for each member of society, which represent the individuals’ preference orders R1, . . . , Rn; and the social utility function u which is the average of these n individual utility functions, i.e. u(x) = 1n ∑ ui (x) for all x ∈ S, represents the social preference order R, when R is defined via the observer’s extended preference Ro on the corresponding impartial lotteries.5 How do we find the particular individual utility functions for which this is true? They are implicitly defined by the particular choice of vNM utility function uo to represent the observer’s extended preference ordering. Suppose that y ∈ �(I x S) is an extended lottery in which the observer is individual i for certain. Let x be the corresponding simple lottery. Then set ui (x) = uo (y), i.e. individual i ’s utility for the simple lottery x equals the observer’s utility for the extended lottery y.6 Relative to the individual utility functions u1, ..., un defined this way, the social utility function u is given by the average utilitarian rule. 5 This is a verbal paraphrase of theorem 9 in Weymark (1991). 6 Since the principle of acceptance is satisfied, the function ui defined by this procedure represents individual i ’s preference order. SOCIAL JUSTICE, GENOMIC JUSTICE AND THE VEIL OF IGNORANCE 49 To summarize, Harsanyi’s impartial observer theorem tries to derive a utilitarian conclusion from three ingredients. These are: (i) the assumption that all individuals, including the observer, are expected utility maximizers; (ii) the principle of acceptance; and (iii) the ethical postulate that society’s choice should be determined by what the impartial observer would choose from behind the veil. The difference between Harsanyi and Rawls stems chiefly from the latter’s rejection of (i). 3. THE SEN/WEYMARK CRITIQUE OF HARSANYI Though formally straightforward, the philosophical significance of the impartial observer theorem is a matter of ongoing controversy; see Mongin (2001) for a recent assessment. Sen (1986) argued that Harsanyi’s theorem does not in fact establish a utilitarian conclusion, in the ordinary sense of utilitarianism, but is merely a representation theorem for social preferences. This criticism was endorsed and further developed by Weymark (1991). The essence of the Sen/Weymark critique is that there is an irreconcilable tension in Harsanyi’s argument. On the one hand he needs to assume that utility is fully interpersonally comparable, i.e. both utility levels and differences can be compared across individuals. (Difference comparability is needed for utilitarianism to be a well-defined doctrine, and level comparability is needed for the impartial observer to be able to make his judgements of extended preference.) On the other hand he assumes that ‘utility’ means utility in the sense of von Neumann and Morgenstern, i.e. a numerical representation of a preference relation over lotteries. Preferences are primary, on the standard vNM picture, and utility derived. This is inherently problematic. One problem is that the vNM theory does not itself tell us how to make the required interpersonal comparisons; but there is a deeper problem. As Weymark stresses, if utility is merely a representation of preference, there is no particular reason to restrict attention to vNM utility functions (i.e. ones that are linear in the probabilities, or expectational). The vNM theorem tells us that if an individual’s preference relation over lotteries satisfies certain axioms, then it ca n be represented by an expectational utility function, but it can equally well be represented by many other utility functions which are not expectational.7 However it is essential to Harsanyi’s theorem that only vNM utility functions are used to represent preferences; without this, 7 If u is a vNM utility representation of a given preference relation R over lotteries, and f (u) is any increasing transformation of u, affine or not, then f (u) will also represent R. On the orthodox view, the reason for employing vNM utility functions, rather than any other, is simply mathematical convenience; as Arrow (1951) said, their merit is ‘stating the laws of rational behaviour in a particularly convenient way’ (p. 10). 50 SAMIR OKASHA the utilitarian conclusion does not go through. But Harsanyi offers no justification for only considering vNM utility functions; he appears to think, wrongly, that their use is mandated rather than merely permitted by the von Neumann–Morgenstern expected utility theorem. Weymark concludes from this that for Harsanyi’s argument to succeed, it must operate with a non-preference based concept of utility. For example, utility could be construed as some kind of mental or hedonic state, à la classical utilitarianism, whose relationship to preferences would then be an empirical matter. (Indeed Harsanyi at times seems to have such a concept in mind.) If such a notion of utility is granted, and certain assumptions about it are made, then Harsanyi’s argument may be salvageable. The assumptions are that utility is real-valued, cardinally measurable, fully interpersonally comparable, and expectational, i.e. the utility of a lottery is its expected utility. This is the basis for a version of Harsanyi’s theorem proposed by Weymark (1991) (his theorem 10). To avoid confusion Weymark talks about well-being rather than utility, and makes the above assumptions about well-being. As in Harsanyi’s original, there is a set of social alternatives, and a set of lotteries over them. Each individual has a well- being function over the lotteries. The impartial observer has a well-being function over the extended alternatives, and the extended lotteries. The ‘principle of welfare identity’ says that the observer’s well-being from an extended alternative in which she is person i for certain equals person i ’s well-being in that alternative; this is the analogue of Harsanyi’s principle of acceptance. Society’s well-being, in any simple lottery, is postulated to equal the observer’s well-being in the corresponding impartial extended lottery, analogously to Harsanyi’s original. Given all this, it is easily shown that society’s well-being, in any social alternative, is the average well- being of the individuals in society; so average utilitarianism is true.8 Weymark’s version of the theorem could be simplified, in that it is not actually necessary to assume that individuals’ well-being functions are defined on lotteries, as well as alternatives. (The same is not true of the observer’s well-being function, obviously.) Even if individual well- being is only defined for the social alternatives themselves, a utilitarian conclusion can still be derived.9 8 The utilitarian conclusion follows very simply when utility or well-being is taken as primitive in the impartial observer model. The fact that the observer’s well-being function is expectational, and satisfies the principle of welfare identity, directly implies that the well-being the observer derives from an impartial extended lottery equals the average individual well-being in the corresponding simple lottery. As Mongin (2001) observes, this is less a ‘theorem’ than a routine application of decision theory. 9 A utilitarian conclusion for the social alternatives themselves, that is. To derive a utilitarian conclusion for the lotteries, as well as the alternatives, requires that the individual well-being functions are defined over lotteries (and are expectational). SOCIAL JUSTICE, GENOMIC JUSTICE AND THE VEIL OF IGNORANCE 51 Weymark argues that his version of the impartial observer theorem, though free from the conceptual problems that plague Harsanyi’s original, rests on assumptions that are hard to defend. That well-being is cardinal and interpersonally comparable is controversial enough; but it is the assumption that it is expectational that Weymark finds especially problematic. Why should it be true that the well-being the observer gets from a lottery equals the expected well-being derived from the prizes, i.e. social alternatives? In the context of Harsanyi’s original argument this question does not arise, since vNM utility is by definition expectational; but the question is pressing for any non-preference based concept of utility, or well-being.10 In section 5, I offer a biological interpretation of Harsanyi’s impartial observer theorem, using Weymark’s version. It turns out that in a biological setting, the assumptions about well-being or utility that are needed to make the theorem work are readily defensible. 4. BIOLOGICAL PRELIMINARIES To explain how the veil-of-ignorance concept applies to Mendelian genetics, some biological preliminaries are necessary. The vast majority of sexually reproducing species are diploid, meaning that their cells contain two copies of each chromosome, one paternal and one maternal. The two copies need not be genetically identical; each gene has a number of variants, or alleles11, and the allele at a given slot on the paternal chromosome may differ from the one at the corresponding slot on the maternal chromosome. These chromosomal slots are known as loci. If the two alleles at a given locus are the same, the organism is homozygotic at that locus, otherwise it is heterozygotic. The genotype of an organism is a specification of the alleles it contains at one or more loci. So if A and a are two alleles at a given locus, there are three possible genotypes at that locus: the homozygotes AA and aa, and the heterozygote Aa. In order to reproduce sexually, diploid organisms produce gametes (e.g. sperm or egg cells) which are haploid, i.e. contain only one of each chromosome pair. Two haploid gametes then fuse to form a diploid zygote, and a new organism is born. Gametes are formed via a cell- division process called meiosis, which reduces the chromosome number by half. So only one member of each chromosome pair ends up in a given gamete. Meiosis proceeds in a number of distinct stages; see Figure 1. Firstly, every chromosome is copied, resulting in a cell that contains two copies 10 Risse (2002) and Broome (1991) have tried to argue, in a related context, that well-being is ‘inherently’ expectational, but it is debatable whether their argument succeeds. 11 In some contexts, biologists use the terms ‘gene’ and ‘allele’ more-or-less interchangeably, a practice that is followed here where there is no risk of confusion. 52 SAMIR OKASHA FIGURE 1. Crossing Over of each maternal and each paternal chromosome. (In Figure 1, which depicts meiosis for a single chromosome pair, this doubling has happened before the diagram starts.) Next a process called ‘crossing over’ occurs, in which the paternal and maternal chromosomes can swap portions of their genetic material. The paternal and maternal chromosomes in each pair line up alongside each other, break at the same point, exchange parts and then join up. Finally, two rounds of cell division take place, resulting in four haploid gametes each containing one of every chromosome pair. So from a single diploid cell, four haploid gametes are ultimately produced. SOCIAL JUSTICE, GENOMIC JUSTICE AND THE VEIL OF IGNORANCE 53 Crossing-over means that a chromosome in a gamete will usually not be a perfect copy of either member of the chromosome pair from which it came. This results in a ‘shuffling’ of genes between parent and daughter chromosomes. If two genes are located at distant ends of a parental chromosome, they may easily be broken up by crossing-over, so will not tend to be transmitted together. But if the genes are located close together on a chromosome, they are likely to be transmitted to a gamete as a unit. Such genes, and the loci they occupy, are said to be ‘linked’. Most of the time meiosis is fair, i.e. each member of a chromosome pair has an equal chance of making it into any gamete. So an Aa heterozyote will produce A gametes and a gametes in equal proportion (on average). This is Mendel’s law of segregation, or Mendel’s first law. But the law has exceptions. In many species, rogue genes have been discovered which can cheat Mendel’s law and get into more than their fair share of gametes. This is known as ‘meiotic drive’ or ‘segregation distortion’; the genes in question are called segregation-distorters. If the A allele is a segregation-distorter, then more than half of the gametes produced by the Aa heretozygote will be A gametes. Segregation-distorters only have evolutionary consequences when they are in heterozygotes. Suppose there are two alleles A and a at a locus, and the A allele is able to distort segregation in its favour. This means that the ratio of A to a gametes produced by an Aa heterozygote will exceed 1:1, so the A allele will increase in frequency in the gene pool, ceteris paribus. By contrast an AA homozygote only produces A gametes anyway (mutation aside), so it makes no difference whether segregation is Mendelian or not. A segregation-distorter allele enjoys an inherent selective advantage over non-distorters at the same locus. If the A allele distorts segregation in its favour and there are no counterbalancing selective pressures, it will sweep to fixation in the population. It is not known how often this has happened in natural populations, since it is very difficult to detect. In other cases the distorter allele does not become fixed, but is maintained in the population at an intermediate frequency. This happens when the distorter allele has negative effects on organismic fitness, which offsets its segregation advantage. Thus suppose that the A allele distorts segregation in its favour, but that organisms with the AA genotype suffer a fitness disadvantage compared to Aa and a a organisms. Then for a range of parameter values, the population will evolve to a stable equilibrium in which both alleles are present. When this happens, segregation-distorters can be detected empirically. Segregation distortion involves a special sort of natural selection, known as ‘intra-genomic selection’, which takes place between the alleles within a single organism. In the example above, the A allele is selected over the a allele within Aa heterozygotes, since it gets into more than 54 SAMIR OKASHA half the gametes. But this is countered by selection at a higher level, i.e. selection between organisms. AA organisms are less fit than Aa and a a , so their total production of gametes is lower. Thus there are two opposing selective forces at work, operating at different hierarchical levels. In effect, the A allele in a heterozygote profits at the expense of its host organism – it reduces the total number of gametes the organism produces, but takes a disproportionate share of the pie for itself. The above examples assume that a segregation-distorter is a gene at a single locus. This is in principle possible, but empirically most cases of segregation-distortion involve two genes at tightly linked loci, working in concert (cf. Lyttle (1991)). In the fruit fly Drosophila melanogaster, an allele at the ‘toxin’ locus, denoted Sd, produces a product that inactivates any gametes that do not produce antidote. Whether a gamete produces antidote depends on which allele it has at a second locus; the Rs p+ allele does not produce antidote, while the Rs p allele does. Since the two loci are tightly linked, the Sd/Rs p pair constitutes an effective system for meiotic drive. An Sd/Rs p chromosome will produce toxin that destroys gametes not containing the Rs p allele; due to linkage, such gametes will not contain the Sd allele either. So both the Sd and Rs p alleles will achieve greater than fifty percent representation in the successful gametes of their host organism, by destroying gametes containing rival alleles. 5. FAIR MENDELIAN SEGREGATION: EVOLUTIONARY CONSIDERATIONS Segregation distortion is the exception not the rule; most of the time meiosis is fair. Since fair meiosis involves complex molecular machinery, it seems probable that it is an evolved feature of organisms, so has a Darwinian explanation. This prompts the question: what is the benefit of fair meiosis? Why would natural selection have favoured it? This question is deceptively simple; we need to ask: ‘benefit for whom?’ An individual gene clearly benefits if it can distort segregation in its favour – that way it will bequeath more copies to subsequent generations. Imagine again two alleles at a locus, A and a . Clearly, the A allele would prefer a segregation scheme of 4:1 in favour of A, for example, over fair 1:1 segregation. Conversely, allele a would prefer segregation to be biased in its favour. So neither allele at the locus in question benefits from fair meiosis per se; both would do better if segregation were biased to their advantage. What about the organism as a whole? Does the whole organism benefit from fair meiosis? The answer is ‘yes’, in many circumstances. The reason is that a distorter will often have harmful effects on its host organism. Ordinarily a gene which harms its host organism will harm its own reproductive interests, so will be selected against. But this is not true SOCIAL JUSTICE, GENOMIC JUSTICE AND THE VEIL OF IGNORANCE 55 if the gene is a segregation-distorter. A distorter gene may spread by natural selection even if it harms its host organism – which implies a conflict of interest between gene and organism. To see this point, suppose allele a is initially fixed at a locus, and then allele A arises by mutation. Allele A has two effects: it distorts segregation in its favour, and it reduces the fitness of its host organism. For concreteness, suppose the fitness scheme is: w(a a ) = 10, w( Aa ) = 9, w( AA) = 8, where these are the numbers of successful gametes produced by an organism of the genotype in question. Suppose that of the 9 successful gametes produced by an Aa heterozygote, 6 are A and 3 are a , on average. Thus the Aa genotype produces fewer successful gametes than the a a genotype, but a disproportionate number of these are A. So despite imposing a fitness cost on its host organism, the mutant A allele is favoured by natural selection when rare. The population evolves to a stable equilibrium where both alleles are present.12 This illustrates how segregation distortion can lead to a conflict of interest between a gene and its host organism. Of course a distorter might not harm its host organism; it could be phenotypically neutral, or even beneficial. In these cases the distorter will quickly sweep to fixation in the population, since its segregation advantage is not offset by any negative effects on organismic fitness. But when distorters are maintained in the population in a polymorphic equilibrium, as empirically is often found, then they must be harming their hosts. The conflict of interest between a distorter allele and its host organism can equally be thought of as a conflict between the distorter allele and the genes at other (unlinked13) loci within the organism. If allele A distorts segregation at its own locus, a gene at an unlinked locus is not directly affected. However if the A allele also reduces organismic fitness, as many distorters do, then genes at other loci suffer. They pay the cost of the reduction in fitness but gain no compensating segregation advantage, so end up bequeathing fewer copies to the next generation. Genes at other loci thus benefit if they can somehow prevent the A allele from distorting segregation, so will be under selection to do so. This is the basis for the explanation of fair meiosis developed by Eshel (1985), who showed that ‘modifier’ genes at unlinked loci, that have the effect of restoring fair meiosis at the locus undergoing drive, will be 12 Presuming mating is random, equilibrium is attained when the population-wide frequencies of the A and a alleles are approximately 0.45 and 0.55 respectively. With these frequencies, the marginal fitnesses of the A and a alleles are equal so there is no further evolutionary change. 13 The qualification ‘unlinked’ is crucial. At any linked locus, there will be selection for genes which increase allele A’s segregation distortion, as they will become preferentially associated with A and will thus gain from the distortion. 56 SAMIR OKASHA favoured by natural selection.14 So a tug-of-war will ensue: the A allele will try to bias segregation in its favour, but alleles at all other unlinked loci in the genome will try to restore meiotic fairness. Since there are many such loci in the genome, they are likely to win the war. The predicted outcome is thus a restoration of fair meiosis. Thus there is a putative evolutionary explanation for why fair meiosis is the rule. This explanation is widely accepted among biologists. The underlying idea in Eshel’s explanation was vividly expressed by Leigh (1977), who spoke of a ‘parliament of genes’ trying to prevent ‘cabals of a few conspiring for their own “selfish profit” at the expense of the “commonwealth”’ (p. 4543). Leigh’s point was that the bulk of the genes in the genome gain nothing from one of their member distorting segregation at its own locus, and potentially stand to lose a lot, given that distorters often reduce organismic fitness; therefore the genes have a collective interest in enforcing fair meiotic division. A different (though equivalent) perspective is that fair meiosis acts to equalize the interests of all the genes in the organism. If meiosis is constrained to be fair, then the only way a gene can benefit itself is to boost the fitness (total gametic output) of the whole organism, which benefits all other genes too. By contrast, if a gene can break Mendel’s law then it can benefit despite harming its host organism, as we have seen. So fair meiosis acts as a unifying force, preventing internal conflict and leading the organism to behave as a single, cohesive entity. The fact of meiotic drive, and the evolutionary pressures it gives rise to, remind us that the unity of the individual organism cannot be taken for granted. We naturally regard an individual organism as a cohesive entity, with a unity of purpose, i.e. all its parts work for the common good. This is often justified, but organismic unity is an evolutionary achievement, and is possible only to the extent that meiotic drive (and other forms of intra-genomic conflict) are kept in check (cf. Ridley 2000). An organism in a sexual species is a temporary coalition of genes whose interests do not necessarily overlap, as they are not all transmitted together. Fair meiosis works to align the genes’ interests, ensuring they work for the common good. If the parliament of genes could not enforce Mendel’s law, harmful genes could spread and organismic integrity would be undermined. How exactly is fair meiosis enforced? The biochemical details are not well understood, but Haig and Grafen (1991) suggest one possible mechanism. Recall that empirically, most cases of segregation distortion involve a pair of genes at tightly linked loci acting in concert – such as the toxin/antidote Sd/Rs p system in Drosophila described above. Given this fact, any way of ‘unlinking’ the two loci, e.g. by increasing the rate 14 A modifier gene is one which affects the phenotypic expression of some other gene in an organism. SOCIAL JUSTICE, GENOMIC JUSTICE AND THE VEIL OF IGNORANCE 57 of crossing over, will tend to restore fair meiosis. The Sd/Rsp system relies critically on the fact that a gamete containing the Sd allele is also likely to contain Rs p, and thus to be immune from the toxin. But if the linkage is broken, then the Sd’s segregation advantage disappears – for then, the toxin it produces will be as likely to kill a gamete containing a copy of itself as of its rival allele. Destroying linkage thus prevents genes like Sd and Rs p from forming a selfish cabal at the expense of the rest of the genome. Thus one way to prevent meiotic drive, Haig and Grafen argue, is to destroy linkage, i.e. to force the genes in question to assort independently. Genes on other chromosomes that can achieve this result will be selectively favoured. More could be said about the evolution of fair meiosis, but the essential points have been made.15 In a sexual species, there is a potential conflict between any individual gene and its host organism. A gene that distorts segregation in its favour can spread despite reducing its host’s fitness. This harms genes at unlinked loci, who are thus under selection to restore fair meiosis if they can. One effect of fair meiosis is to equalize the interests of all the genes, thus ensuring they work for the common good. One way of achieving this is to destroy linkage, given that segregation distortion typically involves linked genes working in concert. 6. MENDELIAN SEGREGATION AND THE VEIL OF IGNORANCE Finally we are in a position to relate Mendelian genetics to the veil of ignorance. The basis for the analogy is fairly clear. When meiosis is fair, then any given allele does not ‘know’ whether it will be transmitted to a particular gamete – the chance that it will is fifty percent. So the allele is behind a veil of ignorance with regard to its presence in each gamete, which ensures that its interests are aligned with its host organism, i.e. it will seek to maximize the organism’s gametic output. Furthermore, an allele that is transmitted to a gamete does not ‘know’ which other alleles (at unlinked loci) are also in the gamete. By forcing genes behind a veil of ignorance, fair meiosis thus randomizes away the information that alleles would need to profit at the expense of their host, or to form selfish cabals with genes at other loci. This analogy may seem limited since it says nothing about choice from behind the veil, a notion central to the Harsanyi/Rawls argument. But in fact the notion of choice (or preference) is implicit in talk of a gene’s ‘interests’ – which is itself short-hand for talking about what natural selection would favour. This permits the analogy to be elaborated as follows. The alleles in an organism correspond to the individuals 15 Crow (1991) is a useful review of work on this topic up to 1991; Úbeda and Haig (2005) discuss some recent developments. 58 SAMIR OKASHA in society, in Harsanyi’s model. The social alternatives are alternative ‘gametic outputs’, i.e. specifications of how many successful gametes the organism leaves and which alleles they contain. Each allele has a ‘preference order’ over the alternatives, determined by how many copies of itself are left in each alternative. The organism itself also has a preference order over the alternatives (analogous to the social preference in Harsanyi’s model), determined by the total gametic output, or organismic fitness, in each alternative. To illustrate, consider a single locus with two alleles A and a . Suppose that for an Aa heterozygote, there are four biologically possible output levels – leaving 0, 1, 2 or 3 successful gametes. All segregation schemes are considered possible. Thus the set of social alternatives S is: {0, A, a , AA, Aa , a A, a a , AAA, AAa , Aa A, Aa a , a AA, a Aa , a a A, a a a } where ‘ AAa ’, for example, means that the organism leaves three successful gametes, the first two of which contain A and the third a . (Note that the order in which the gametes are produced matters, so AAa and Aa A are different alternatives.) The A allele prefers alternative x to y iff it leaves more copies in x than y; thus the A allele prefers alternative AAa to a a a , for example. The a allele has the converse preference. The organism itself is indifferent between AAa and a a a , since its fitness is the same in each (see Table 1). All alleles at unlinked loci (not modelled here) have the same preference order as the organism; they have no interest per se in whether meiosis is fair at the A/a locus.16 Note also that the A allele prefers Aa to a a a , despite total gametic output being greater in the latter. This illustrates the fact that the A allele, if permitted to choose, could easily harm the interests of the whole organism. It bears emphasis that talk of ‘interests’, ‘choice’ and ‘preference’ in this and other evolutionary contexts is fully legitimate, as it can be cashed out precisely and non-metaphorically in terms of natural selection. In saying that the A allele ‘prefers’ alternative Aa to a a a , we mean that if the A allele could exert causal influence over which of these alternatives obtained, natural selection would lead it to bring about the Aa alternative. Similarly, in saying that the organism is indifferent between AAa and a a a we mean that selection would have no tendency to favour an organism producing one rather than the other of these gametic outputs. A related point is that the ‘preference order’ of each allele (and the organism) is not primitive, but rather derives from its fitness in each alternative. It is because allele A has a fitness of two in alternative AAa and a fitness 16 Note that this does not conflict with the standard argument, expounded in section 5, that selection at the organism level (or at unlinked loci) will tend to restore fair meiosis. That argument presumes that the segregation-distorter alleles will have a negative effect on organismic fitness, but this is not being assumed at this juncture. SO C IA L JU ST IC E, G EN O M IC JU ST IC E A N D T H E V EIL O F IG N O R A N C E 5 9 Rank A’s preference a’s preference Organism’s preference 1. AAA a a a AAA, AAa , Aa A, a AA, Aa a , a Aa , a a A, a a a 2. AA, AAa , Aa A, a AA a a , Aa a , a Aa , a a A AA, Aa , a A, a a 3. A, Aa , a A, Aa a , a Aa , a a A a , Aa , a A, AAa , Aa A, a AA A, a 4. a a a , a a , a , 0 AAA, AA, A, 0 0 TABLE 1. Preference orders over gametic outputs 60 SAMIR OKASHA of zero in alternative a a a that it prefers the former to the latter. So the preference ordering is induced by the fitness function. This is the converse of the usual situation in decision theory, where preferences are primitive and their numerical representations derived. The significance of this will become clear. Since the A and a alleles have different preference orders over the social alternatives, and the organism itself has a different preference order again, there is considerable scope for internal conflict – selection will tend to disrupt the integrity of the organism. It is here that fair meiosis comes into play; as we have seen, it has the effect of aligning the interests of all parties. To represent this in the Harsanyi framework, we first need to introduce lotteries over the set S, i.e. probability distributions over possible gametic outputs. This permits two types of randomness or uncertainty to be modelled: about how many successful gametes the organism produces, and about which genes they contain. The former arises because survival and reproduction are stochastic – two organisms of identical genotype won’t necessarily enjoy the same reproductive success. Though important in many evolutionary models, this factor is not especially relevant here. The latter arises because of the meiotic process, and is our prime concern. Suppose that meiosis is fair, and that the organism definitely leaves two successful gametes (so there is no uncertainty of the first type.) This picks out a unique lottery over S, which has P ( AA) = P ( Aa ) = P (a A) = P (a a ) = 14 and zero probability for every other alternative. This is because with fair meiosis, any gamete has an equal chance of receiving the A or a allele, with independence across gametes. Clearly, any given alternative to fair meiosis, e.g. 3:1 in favour of A, also picks out a unique lottery, once the total number of successful gametes has been specified. What about preference over lotteries? How do we make sense of the idea that allele A prefers one lottery to another? The natural way is to assume that an allele evaluates lotteries by the criterion of expected fitness, and so would prefer, i.e. be selected to bring about, the lottery in which its expected fitness is highest; similarly for the organism. Thus allele A’s evaluation of the lottery described above, in which two successful gametes are produced and meiosis is fair, equals 1 4 (2) + 1 4 (1) + 1 4 (1) + 1 4 (0) = 1. Similarly, the organism’s evaluation of this lottery equals 1 4 (2) + 1 4 (2) + 1 4 (2) + 1 4 (2) = 2. Modulo this assumption, it is straightforward to derive a preference order for each allele, and for the organism, over the entire lottery set. SOCIAL JUSTICE, GENOMIC JUSTICE AND THE VEIL OF IGNORANCE 61 Importantly, there is a real biological rationale for assuming that lotteries are evaluated by expected fitness, namely that this is the evaluation that natural selection will make. When the fitness of an organism (or genotype) is a random quantity, it is well-known that natural selection will select for maximization of expected fitness, given two conditions. These are: (i) that the population is very large, and (ii) the randomness is independent across organisms. Condition (i) is standard in evolutionary theory. To understand condition (ii), suppose an organism of a given genotype leaves 1 or 3 offspring with equi-probability. If each organism of the genotype faces an independent 50:50 gamble on 1 or 3 offspring, e.g. a separate coin is flipped for each, then condition (ii) is satisfied. But if the risk is correlated, e.g. a single coin flip decides whether a ll organisms of the genotype leave 1 or a ll leave 3, then condition (ii) is violated.17 In some contexts, assuming independence across organisms (or ‘uncorrelated risk’) would be unjustified. For example, if an organism’s fitness varies randomly because of the weather, the independence assumption would clearly be wrong, since the weather affects many organisms. But in the present context, where our interest is the random variation in an organism’s gametic output due to meiosis, the assumption is fully justified. Suppose again that an organism of genotype Aa definitely leaves two successful gametes and that meiosis is fair, so P ( AA) = P ( Aa ) = P (a A) = P (a a ) = 14 . Clearly, this probability distribution is independent across all Aa organisms, given how meiosis works. Knowing that one Aa organism produced AA, for example, tells us nothing about the output of any other. More precisely, if we consider lotteries in which total gametic output is certain, so the uncertainty pertains only to the distribution of the output, then the independence assumption is justified. Expected fitness is thus the right criterion by which an allele, or an organism, should evaluate such lotteries. We can now use our Harsanyi-style framework to give precise expression to the idea that fair meiosis equalizes the interests of the A and a alleles, thus preventing conflict. The two alleles have different preference orders over the set S, and thus also over the lottery set �S, as we have seen. But consider the subset of lotteries that are meiotically fair, i.e. which are compatible with each allele having an equal chance of entering any gamete. The A and a alleles will evaluate the meiotically fair lotteries identically, and thus have identical preference orderings over them. To see this, consider again the lottery in which meiosis is fair, and the organism definitely leaves two successful gametes, i.e. < P ( AA) = P ( Aa ) = P (a A) = P (a a ) = 1 4 >. The A allele’s evaluation of this is 1 4 (2) + 14 (1) + 14 (1) + 14 (0) = 1, which 17 These two extremes – independence across gametes and perfect correlation – are the opposite ends of a spectrum. Intermediate degrees of correlation are also possible. 62 SAMIR OKASHA is the same as the a allele’s evaluation. The same will be true of any meiotically fair lottery. Note also that the A and a allele’s preference ordering over the subset of meiotically fair lotteries will coincide with that of the organism – so lotteries will be ranked according to average (or total) gametic output, i.e. in a ‘utilitarian’ way. To illustrate, compare the meiotically fair lotteries in which the organism definitely leaves one and two successful gametes respectively, i.e. < P ( A) = P (a ) = 12 > and < P ( AA) = P ( Aa ) = P (a A) = P (a a ) = 14 >. The organism obviously prefers the latter, as its fitness is twice as high as in the former. Each allele’s expected fitness is also twice as high in the latter lottery, so its interests are aligned perfectly with the organism’s. Therefore if meiosis is constrained to be fair, the only way that an allele can boost its expected representation in the next generation is by boosting the organism’s total gametic output. This shows that two standard pieces of biological wisdom about fair meiosis are neatly captured by casting the issue in a Harsanyi-style framework. That fair meiosis aligns the interests of competing alleles, with each other and with the host organism, is reflected in the fact that their preference orders coincide over the subset of lotteries that are meiotically fair. The device of fair meiosis, therefore, is the organism’s solution to the social contract problem. This is interesting, and vindicates the idea of treating the alleles in an organism as individuals in a society, with potentially divergent interests. But it does not quite forge a logical link with Harsanyi’s own argument. Recall that Harsanyi uses the device of a hypothetical impartial observer to construct a social ordering of a ll lotteries (and thus alternatives) – which turns out to be the utilitarian ordering. We have represented fair meiosis, however, as effecting a restriction on the set of lotteries to the ‘meiotically fair’ ones; on this subset, each allele’s ordering is the utilitarian ordering. There is a similarity here to Harsanyi’s argument, but not a exact parallel. Indicative of this is that the notion of an extended lottery, central to Harsanyi’s argument, played no role in our representation of fair meiosis. Is it possible to forge a more direct link? It turns out that it is. 7. AN EXPLICIT LINK BETWEEN FAIR MEIOSIS AND THE IMPARTIAL OBSERVER THEOREM Harsanyi introduces extended lotteries in order to model the notion of impartiality, or justice. He needs to do this since his social alternatives are purely abstract. But in our biological application the alternatives have internal structure – an alternative specifies how many resources (gametes) go to each individual. This permits the notion of impartiality SOCIAL JUSTICE, GENOMIC JUSTICE AND THE VEIL OF IGNORANCE 63 to be modelled more simply, without the need for extended lotteries, via symmetry considerations. Call a lottery over gametic outputs symmetric if it is invariant under permutation of alleles. Thus for example, the lottery < P ( AAA) = P (a a a ) = 12 > is symmetric, since if every ‘A’ is swapped to an ‘ a ’ we end up with exactly the same lottery. Note that if a lottery is symmetric, the expected number of A and a alleles it yields is the same, so the two alleles will evaluate it identically. From an individual allele’s point of view, symmetry has an obvious epistemic interpretation. Symmetric lotteries are ones in which the allele is deprived of knowledge about its own identity. For the A allele, the lottery < P ( AAA) = P (a a a ) = 12 > corresponds to certain knowledge that its host organism will produce three identical successful gametes, but ignorance about who it will be – the lucky or the unlucky one. This interpretation suggests a natural link with Harsanyi’s notion of an impartial extended lottery. Note that all meiotically fair lotteries are symmetric though not vice- versa. Meiotically fair lotteries are ones in which each allele has a given chance of entering any gamete, with independence across gametes. So the lottery < P ( AAA) = P (a a a ) = 12 > is not meiotically fair, since although each allele has an equal chance of being found in (for example) the second successful gamete, independence across gametes is not satisfied – the allele found in the second successful gamete will definitely be found in the first and third. So in meiotically fair lotteries, each allele is deprived of knowledge of its own identity, and also of conditional knowledge of its own identity given any information about the organism’s gametic output. So we have: meiotically fair lotteries ⊂ symmetric lotteries ⊂ all lotteries. To each alternative in S, there is exactly one meiotically fair lottery which gives that alternative non-zero probability, and which definitely yields the same total number of gametes as that alternative. Call this the meiotically fair lottery that corresponds to the alternative. Thus to the alternative Aa , for example, there corresponds the meiotically fair lottery < P ( AA) = P ( Aa ) = P (a A) = P (a a ) = 14 >; note that this lottery also corresponds to alternatives AA, a A and a a . More generally, the set S can be partitioned into equivalence classes of alternatives with the same corresponding meiotically fair lotteries. These can be regarded as ‘information sets’, i.e. alternatives which neither allele can tell apart, under the supposition that meiosis will be fair. We can then derive an evaluation, and thus an ordering, of the alternatives in S for a given allele ‘from behind the meiotic veil’. Ordinarily, the A allele evaluates an alternative by how many copies it leaves in that alternative. But with fair meiosis in place, the allele can’t discriminate between alternatives in the same information set; and thus is forced to substitute their evaluation of the corresponding meiotically 64 SAMIR OKASHA Alterna�ves S Lo�eries S Meio�cally fair lo�eries Extended alterna�ves I x S Extended lo�eries � � (I x S) Impar�al extended lo�eries FIGURE 2. Two ways of representing impartiality fair lottery. Thus the A allele’s ‘veiled’ evaluation of alternative Aa , for example, equals their evaluation of the lottery < P ( AA) = P ( Aa ) = P (a A) = P (a a ) = 14 >, which equals 1; allele a ’s ‘veiled’ evaluation is the same. This evaluation then induces a veiled ordering of the alternatives, from best to worst. Now recall Harsanyi’s approach. To each alternative Harsanyi associates a unique impartial extended lottery. Let us apply this to our genetic example, where the alternatives are gametic outputs. Thus for example, Harsanyi’s procedure associates to alternative Aa the lottery < P ( Aa , A) = P ( Aa , a ) = 12 >; this can be read ‘alternative Aa for certain, with equal probability of being person A or person a ’. Harsanyi then derives a social ordering of the alternatives, by postulating that it equals the observer’s ordering of the corresponding impartial extended lotteries. An explicit link between the two ways of modelling impartiality is now possible. For each alternative in S, there corresponds to it a unique impartial extended lottery, and a unique meiotically fair lottery (Figure 2). We can then order the alternatives in S two ways: by how the observer would order the corresponding impartial extended lotteries, or by how one of the alleles would order the corresponding meiotically fair lotteries. But these two give exactly the same result – the average utilitarian ordering. To see this, compare the two alternatives Aa and a a . The impartial observer, to evaluate these, would compare the lotteries < P ( Aa , A) = P ( Aa , a ) = 12 SOCIAL JUSTICE, GENOMIC JUSTICE AND THE VEIL OF IGNORANCE 65 >, and < P (a a , A) = P (a a , a ) = 12 >. Assuming the principle of welfare identity, and that the observer’s valuation function is expectational, the former is evaluated as 12 (1) + 12 (1) = 1, the latter as 12 (0) + 12 (2) = 1. So the observer deems the alternatives equally good. Now consider how the A allele (or the a allele) would evaluate Aa and a a from behind the meiotic veil. Since both alternatives are in the same information set, the A allele would evaluate them both as 14 (2) + 14 (1) + 14 (1) + 14 (0) = 1. So both ways of ordering yield the result that Aa and a a are as good as each other. This result generalizes easily, yielding: Proposition 1: Let S be the set of alternative gametic outputs. Let R be the ordering of S given by the impartial observer’s ordering of the corresponding impartial alternative lotteries (assuming the principle of welfare identity, and that the observer’s valuation function is expectational). Let R′ be the ordering of S given by any allele’s ordering of the corresponding meiotically fair lottery. Then, R = R′. Proof: see Appendix Proposition 1 shows that the link between Harsanyi’s way of modelling social justice, via the device of an impartial observer, and the natural way of modelling genomic justice, via a restriction on the set of lotteries to the meiotically fair ones, is actually quite intimate. In reality, the two amount to the same thing: they capture the notion of impartiality in different, but equivalent, ways. The main difference is the greater generality of Harsanyi’s approach, since it does not require that the social alternatives have structure. A second, minor difference is that Harsanyi’s way of deriving a social ordering of the alternatives derives from a more general ordering of the lotteries; while the ‘meiotically fair’ lottery approach yields a direct ordering of the alternatives. But this difference is more real than apparent. On the meiotically fair approach, it would be straightforward to extend the ‘social’ ordering to the full lottery set �S, if we wished, simply by stipulating that a lottery’s valuation is its expected valuation. Importantly, proposition 1 could be strengthened by considering symmetric lotteries rather than meiotically fair lotteries. To each alternative in S, there corresponds a set of symmetric lotteries each of which definitely yields the same total number of gametes as that alternative, but only one of which is meiotically fair. However, an allele will evaluate all of these symmetric lotteries identically, by the average utilitarian rule. Therefore, proposition 1 would be true if for ‘meiotically fair’ lottery we substituted any member of the class of symmetric lotteries that correspond to the alternative in question. That is, restricting the permissible lotteries to the meiotically fair ones is a way, but not the 66 SAMIR OKASHA only way, of forcing alleles to substitute the organism’s interest for their own. This last observation raises an important question. We have been assuming, with biological orthodoxy, that the function of fair meiosis is to unify the interests of the genes in an organism. But fair meiosis, which amounts to flipping a separate fair coin for each gamete that is produced, is not the only way to achieve this task. Instead, an Aa heterozygote could flip one coin for all the gametes to be produced, i.e. they all get allele A or all get allele a , with equal probability. If two successful gametes are definitely produced, the resulting lottery is < P ( AA) = P (a a ) = 12 > – which is symmetric though not meiotically fair. A veil of ignorance of this type would also lead alleles to evaluate lotteries by average gametic output. Why did evolution not solve the problem of conflicting interests this way? I do not know the answer to this question. It may be that using a separate coin flip for each gamete is the simplest way to implement symmetry, or there may be an underlying evolutionary reason why the allocation of genes to gametes should be independent across gametes, i.e. some adaptive advantage to this independence. Whatever the answer, this question highlights the fact that not all aspects of diploid genetics can be accounted for by the parallel between Harsanyi’s veil of ignorance and its Mendelian counterpart. This is not really surprising; if anything it is surprising that the parallel extends as far as it does. What exactly is the upshot of proposition 1? It shows, in a precise manner, that the way fair meiosis leads alleles to align their interest with the whole organism is identical to the way that the veil of ignorance leads Harsanyi’s impartial observer to align her interests with those of society as a whole – where the latter are defined by the average utilitarian rule. Of course the veil of ignorance is a mere thought experiment for Harsanyi and Rawls, so it is remarkable that the underlying principle behind it – that randomization can serve to align the interests of competing agents – finds an embodiment in real biological systems. Note also that the biological instantiation of the principle corresponds better to Harsanyi’s than to Rawls’s version of the argument, in that the former’s utilitarian conclusion clearly holds in the biological case. From behind the meiotic veil, an allele will use the average utilitarian rule to evaluate alternatives, given standard biological assumptions. In a sense, our biological version of the impartial observer theorem is actually superior to Harsanyi’s original. Recall the Sen/Weymark challenge to Harsanyi: to justify properly his assumption that utility (well-being) is both expectational and inter-personally comparable. This challenge is straightforward to meet in the biological case, where utility is replaced by fitness, and the genes in the organism are the individuals in society. Fitness is trivially (fully) comparable across genes (and SOCIAL JUSTICE, GENOMIC JUSTICE AND THE VEIL OF IGNORANCE 67 organisms); indeed the whole point of the fitness concept is to permit comparisons between biological units (genes, genotypes and organisms). A gene’s fitness, as understood here, is simply the number of copies left in the next generation, and an organism’s fitness means its total gametic contribution to the next generation. So inter-personal comparability is unproblematic in the biological case. Moreover, the assumption that the valuation function is expectational, which is crucial to Harsanyi’s theorem, has a real biological rationale, as noted earlier. For when risk is uncorrelated, the ‘right’ way for a gene (or an organism) to evaluate a lottery is to use the expected value of that lottery – in that this is the evaluation that matters to natural selection. With uncorrelated risk, a gene which codes for lottery L 1 will be selected over one which codes for L 2 if and only if the expected number of copies it leaves in L 1 is greater than in L 2. So the ‘expectational’ nature of the valuation function, for which Harsanyi offered no good argument, admits of a genuine rationale in our biological application of the theorem. There is a certain irony in this. At first blush, the idea of applying Harsanyi’s theorem to Mendelian genetics may seem implausible, a rather strained analogy. But closer examination reveals that the connection is quite intimate – the principle that Harsanyi discovered really is instantiated in genetic systems. Moreover in the genetic case, the Sen/Weymark criticism cuts no ice. Sen and Weymark were no doubt right that Harsanyi’s theorem does not amount to a ‘proof’ of classical utilitarianism, but Harsanyi’s underlying point – that the veil of ignorance leads to a utilitarian evaluation rule given certain assumptions – was of course correct. The problem was that the assumptions in question were ones that Harsanyi could not justify. But in the biological case the corresponding assumptions can be justified, and the analogue of utilitarianism – that organisms, and their constituent genes, should try to maximize total gametic output – actually holds true. 8. COMPARISON WITH RIDLEY’S ANALYSIS In his book Mendel’s Demon, the biologist Mark Ridley (2000) provides an extended discussion of how the veil-of-ignorance concept applies to ge- netics. My analysis differs from Ridley’s in two main ways. Firstly, Ridley focuses exclusively on Rawls’s rather than Harsanyi’s version of the veil- of-ignorance argument. However Harsanyi’s version is more relevant for the parallel with genetics, both because it is formally elaborated, which allows the parallel to be made precise, and because his decision-theoretic assumptions make good sense in a biological context. Indicative of this is that Harsanyi’s utilitarian conclusion holds true in biological systems with fair meiosis, while Rawls’s maximin conclusion does not. 68 SAMIR OKASHA Secondly, Ridley’s view of how the veil-of-ignorance concept applies to genetics is different from our own. Recall from section 4 that two sorts of randomization occur in genetics. Firstly, one of each chromosome pair is allocated at random to a gamete, when meiosis is fair. Secondly, crossing over breaks up linkage, which means that whether an allele at one chromosomal locus gets in to a particular gamete is independent of whether an allele at another locus does. As a result, selfish cabals that subvert the group’s interests cannot form. This helps keep meiosis fair, given that empirically, successful distortion of segregation requires genes at two loci to work in concert (as in the Sd/Rs p system in Dr oso phi la mela noga ster ). So the second sort of randomization helps stabilize the first. In our analysis, it is the first sort of randomization that occupies centre-stage, for it is here that the link with the Harsanyi/Rawls argument is strongest. Just as the veil of ignorance leads Harsanyi’s impartial observer to choose the option that maximizes society’s total welfare, so the Mendelian veil of ignorance (i.e. fair meiosis) leads genes to choose the option that maximizes their organism’s total gametic output, thus equalizing their individual interests with that of the collective. However, Ridley’s emphasis is on the second sort of randomization, i.e. the genetic recombination caused by crossing over. It is here that he thinks the analogy with Rawls’s argument works best (p. 200). But this seems questionable. The main effect of recombination is to deprive genes of information about the identity of genes at other loci, which prevents selfish cabals forming, as Ridley emphasizes. This is an important point, but it has no clear counterpart in the Rawls/Harsanyi argument. The latter involves a single individual – the impartial observer – uncertain about which member of society he will become. The uncertainty does not concern the characteristics of other members of society – or at least, any such uncertainty is strictly irrelevant to the decision problem that the impartial observer faces. So the second sort of randomization, at least in so far as its cabal-stopping consequences are what matters, has no parallel in the Harsanyi/Rawls story.18 My disagreement with Ridley over how the veil-of-ignorance concept applies to genetics is related to the difference between proximate and ultimate explanations. Ridley emphasizes that recombination prevents 18 To be fair to Ridley, he also discusses another consequence of crossing over, to which this criticism does not apply. Following Haig and Grafen (1991), he argues that meoisis is designed to prevent the spread of ‘sister killer’ genes, which gain a transmission advantage by causing their host gamete to kill its sister gamete after meiotic cell division. Crossing over frustrates such sister killer genes, as it means that a putative sister killer doesn’t ‘know’ whether a copy of itself will be found in the sister gamete or not, so is just as likely to harm as to help itself. This consequence of crossing over is distinct from its cabal-stopping consequences. Thanks to an anonymous referee for this observation. SOCIAL JUSTICE, GENOMIC JUSTICE AND THE VEIL OF IGNORANCE 69 selfish cabals forming, and thus deprives genes of the information they would need to cheat Mendel’s first law. This helps keep meiosis fair, given empirical facts about how systems of segregation-distortion actually work. So the second sort of randomization is part of the proximate mechanism by which fair meiosis is maintained. But this says nothing about why fair meiosis is adaptively advantageous in the first place. The first sort of randomization, by contrast, addresses this ultimate question. By equalizing the chances that each allele at a locus will enter a given gamete, the interests of genes are aligned, with each other and with the whole organism. Selection at the organism level will therefore tend to produce fair meiosis. The contrast between the two types of randomization, therefore, is in part a contrast between a particular mechanism by which fair meiosis is in fact stabilized, and the evolutionary consequences that follow from meiosis being fair, however this fairness is achieved. It makes sense that a biological version of the Harsanyi/Rawls argument should have an ultimate orientation. For the Harsanyi/Rawls argument involves the notion of utility, or welfare, applied to both individuals and whole societies. The biological analogue is the notion of fitness, which also applies to both individual genes and whole organisms. But the notion of fitness is the paradigmatically ultimate notion; questions of fitness concern evolutionary consequences, not proximate mechanisms. Despite these criticisms, Ridley’s treatment is insightful and provided the inspiration for the foregoing analysis. Ridley concludes his discussion by saying that ‘Rawls’s mechanism in a way applies more powerfully to genes than it does to human beings’ (p. 200). If ‘Rawls’ is replaced with ‘Harsanyi’, then I think this conclusion is exactly right. As we have seen, the impartial observer argument as applied to humans is in fact fraught with difficulty. The assumptions that Harsanyi uses in his theorem are difficult to justify in the rational choice context that he was operating in. In the biological context, by contrast, the assumptions are straightforward to justify, and the utilitarian conclusion actually holds true. Individual genes do in fact act to maximize their organism’s gametic output, as a result of the fairness of meiosis, so they behave like utilitarian agents. 9. CONCLUSION This paper has explored a parallel between the veil-of-ignorance concept in social ethics and in evolutionary genetics. I have argued that the parallel is a genuine one that runs deep and has real explanatory power. In particular, there is an intriguing biological analogue of Harsanyi’s impartial observer argument that is free from the difficulties that plague Harsanyi’s original. The principle that Harsanyi discovered is actually instantiated in the genetic systems of sexually reproducing organisms, 70 SAMIR OKASHA and ensures that their constituent genes work for the good of the whole organism. The parallel I have developed derives from the fact that utility and fitness play isomorphic roles in rational choice theory and evolutionary theory respectively. This role-isomorphism has been noted before by many authors, particularly in relation to decision-making in strategic contexts, but has only rarely been applied in relation to social choice.19 However there is no good reason for this, since the basic premise of social choice – the existence of individuals in a society with divergent interests – is directly applicable to many biological systems. Future work will be needed to tell whether this conceptual link can be fruitfully exploited. REFERENCES Arrow, K. 1951. Social Choice and Individual Values. New York: Wiley. Binmore, K. 2006. Natural Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Broome, J. 1991. Weighing Goods. Oxford: Blackwell. Conradt, L. and C. List 2009. Group decisions in humans and animals: a survey. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 364: 719–742. Crow, J.F. 1991. Why is Mendelian segregation so exact? Bioessays 13: 305–312. Dawkins, R. 1976. The Selfish Gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Eshel, I. 1985. Evolutionary genetic stability of Mendelian segregation and the role of free recombination in the chromosomal system. American Naturalist 125: 412–420. Frank, S.A. 2003. Repression of competition and the evolution of cooperation. Evolution 57: 693–705. Godfrey-Smith, P. 2009. Darwinian Populations and Natural Selection. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Haig, D. 1997. The social gene. In Behavioural Ecology, 4th edition, eds. J.R. Krebs and N.B. Davies, 284–304. Oxford: Blackwell. Haig, D. and C.T. Bergstrom 1995. Multiple mating, sperm competition and meiotic drive. Journal of Evolutionary Biology 8: 265–282. Haig, D. and A. Grafen 1991. Genetic scrambling as a defense against meiotic drive. Journal of Theoretical Biology 153: 531–558. Hamilton, W.D. 1964. The genetical evolution of social behaviour, i and ii. Journal of Theoretical Biology 7: 1–52. Harsanyi, J.C. 1953. Cardinal utility in welfare economics and in the theory of risk-taking. Journal of Political Economy 61: 434–435. Harsanyi, J.C. 1955. Cardinal welfare, individualistic ethics, and interpersonal comparisons of utility. Journal of Political Economy 63: 309–321. Leigh, E.G. jr. 1971. Adaptation and Diversity. San Francisco: Freeman Cooper. Leigh, E.G. jr. 1977. How does selection reconcile individual advantage with the good of the group? Proceedings of the National Academy of the Sciences USA 74: 4542–4546. List, C. 2004. Democracy in animal groups: a political science perspective. Trends in Ecology and Evolution 19: 168–9. Lyttle, T.W. 1991. Segregation distorters. Annual Review of Genetics 25: 511–557. 19 Okasha (2009) explores conceptual connections between social choice theory and the theory of multi-level selection, which deals with natural selection in a hierarchical world. Other applications of social choice-theoretic ideas to the biological realm include Conradt and List (2009) and List (2004), which focus on group decision making. SOCIAL JUSTICE, GENOMIC JUSTICE AND THE VEIL OF IGNORANCE 71 Mongin, P. 2001. The impartial observer theorem of social ethics. Economics and Philosophy 17: 147–149. Okasha, S. 2009. Individuals, groups, fitness and utility: multi-level selection meets social choice theory. Biology and Philosophy 24: 561–584. Rawls, J. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Ridley, M. 2000. Mendel’s Demon: Gene Justice and the Complexity of Life. London: Weidenfeld and Nicholson. Risse, M. 2002. Harsanyi’s ‘utilitarian theorem’ and utilitarianism. Noûs 36: 550–577. Roemer, J.E. 1998. Theories of Distributive Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Sen, A.K. 1976. Welfare inequalities and Rawlsian axiomatics. Theory and Decision 7: 243–262. Sen, A.K. 1977. Non-linear social welfare functions: a reply to Professor Harsanyi. In Foundational Problems in the Special Sciences, eds. R. Butts and J. Hintikka, 297–302. Dordrecht: Reidel. Sen, A.K. 1986. Social choice theory. In Handbook of Mathematical Economics III, eds. M.D. Intriligator and K.J. Arrow, 1073–1181. Amsterdam: North Holland. Skyrms, B. 1996. Evolution of the Social Contract. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Sober, E. 1998. Three differences between evolution and deliberation. In Modelling Rationality, Morality and Evolution, ed. P. Danielson, 408–422. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Úbeda, F. and D. Haig 2005. On the evolutionary stability of Mendelian Segregation. Genetics 170: 1345–1357. Vickrey, W.S. 1945. Measuring marginal utility by reaction to risk. Econometrica 13: 319–333. Weymark, J. 1991. A reconsideration of the Harsanyi–Sen debate on utilitarianism. In Interpersonal Comparisons of Well-being, eds. J. Elster and J.E. Roemer, 225–320. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. A. PROOF OF PROPOSITION 1 S is the set of alternative gametic outputs. So each x ∈ S is a finite sequence of As and a s, e.g. Aa Aa a AAa . Let Nx be the total number of gametes produced in alternative x. Let Ax be the total number of A gametes produced in alternative x. Let x′ be the impartial extended lottery that corresponds to x. So x′ ≡ < P (x, A) = P (x, a ) = 12 >. Let x′′ be the meiotically fair lottery that corresponds to x. Let Vo be the impartial observer’s valuation function. Let VA be the A allele’s valuation function. Let Va be the a allele’s valuation function. We wish to show that Vo (x′) = VA(x′′). Consider the impartial extended lottery x′ ≡ < P (x, A) = P (x, a ) = 12 >. By the principle of welfare identity, and the fact that Vo (x′) is expectational, we have: Vo (x′) = 12 VA(x) + 12 Va (x). But VA(x) = Ax and Va (x) = Nx − Ax . Therefore Vo (x′) = 1 2 Nx . Next, consider the meiotically fair lottery x′′. x′′ is an equiprobable lottery over 2 Nx alternatives in S. In each of these alternatives, the number of A alleles ranges from 0 to Nx . The proportion of alternatives in which there are exactly z A alleles is: 1 2Nx (Nx z ) . So VA(x′′) = 12Nx . ∑Nx z=0 z. (Nx z ) = 12 Nx . Therefore Vo (x′) = VA(x′′) = 12 Nx . That is, for any alternative x ∈ S, the impartial observer’s valuation of the corresponding impartial extended lottery x′ equals the A allele’s valuation of the corresponding meiotically fair lottery x′′. QE D work_ajprvlvltbdl7oj3lid5durnti ---- Critical Race Theory An Introduction Richard Delgado and Jean Stefancic Foreword by Angela Harris NEW YORK UNIVERSITY PRESS New York and London II Contents Acknowledgments Foreword by Angela Harris Introduction A. What Is Critical Race Theory? B. Early Origins C. Relationship to Other Movements D. Principal Figures E. Spin-off Movements F. Basic Tenets of Critical Race Theory G. How Much Racism Is There in the World? H. Organization of This Book Questions and Continents for Chapter I Suggested Readings Hallmark Critical Race Theory Thèmes A. Interest Convergence, Material Determinism, and Racial Realism B. Revisionist History C. Critique of Liberalism D. Structural Determinism 1. Tools of Thought and the Dilemma of Law Reform 1 2 3 4 5 6 6 9 11 13 14 15 16 20 21 25 26 XI xii I Contents III IV 2. The Empathie Fallacy Classroom Exercise 3. Serving Two Masters 4. Race Remédies Law as a Homeostatic Device Questions and Continents for Chapter II Suggested Readings Légal Storytelling and Narrative Analysis A. Opening a Window onto Ignored or Alternative Realities B. Counterstorytelling C. Cure for Silencing D. Storytelling in Court E. Storytelling on the Défensive Questions and Conintents for Chapter III Suggested Readings Looking Inward A. Intersectionaliry B. Essentialism and Anti-Essentialism C. Nationalism versus Assimilation Classroom Exercise Questions and Comments for Chapter IV Suggested Readings Power and the Shape of Knowledge A. The Black-White Binary B. Critical White Studies Classroom Exercise C. Other Developments: Latino and Asian Critical Thoughr, Critical Race Feminism, Queer-Crit Theory Questions and Comments for Chapter V Suggested Readings 27 29 30 31 33 34 37 39 42 43 45 46 47 48 51 51 56 59 63 64 65 67 67 74 80 81 84 85 VI VII VIII Contents Critiques and Responses to Criticism Classroom Exercise Questions and Comments for Chapter VI Suggested Readings Critical Race Theory Today A. The 1990s B. Capitalism on the Rampage 1. Unmasking Color Blindness 2. Race, Class, Welfare, and Poverty 3. Globalization C. Power D. Identity Classroom Exercise Questions and Comments for Chapter VII Suggested Readings Conclusion A. The Future B. A Critical Race Agenda for the New Century C. Likely Responses to Critical Race Theory 1. Critical Race Theory Becomes the New Civil Rights Orthodoxy 2. Critical Race Theory Marginalized and Ignored 3. Critical Race Theory Analyzed, but Rejected 4. Partial Incorporation Classroom Exercise Questions and Comments for Chapter VIII Suggested Readings Glossary of Ternis Index About the Authors 1 xiii 87 95 97 98 101 101 102 103 107 111 113 120 121 123 125 129 129 131 133 133 134 134 135 135 137 138 141 157 167 work_am65pdhfqrckdd2y5favifcb5i ---- [PDF] Engineering and Social Justice | Semantic Scholar Skip to search formSkip to main content> Semantic Scholar's Logo Search Sign InCreate Free Account You are currently offline. Some features of the site may not work correctly. DOI:10.2200/S00117ED1V01Y200805ETS007 Corpus ID: 12253774Engineering and Social Justice @inproceedings{Riley2008EngineeringAS, title={Engineering and Social Justice}, author={D. Riley}, booktitle={Engineering and Social Justice}, year={2008} } D. Riley Published in Engineering and Social… 2008 Sociology, Computer Science Abstract The profession of engineering in the United States has historically served the status quo, feeding an ever-expanding materialistic and militaristic culture, remaining relatively unresponsive to public concerns, and without significant pressure for change from within. This book calls upon engineers to cultivate a passion for social justice and peace and to develop the skill and knowledge set needed to take practical action for change within the profession. Because many engineers do not… Expand View via Publisher trincoll.edu Save to Library Create Alert Cite Launch Research Feed Share This Paper 216 CitationsHighly Influential Citations 23 Background Citations 102 Methods Citations 11 Results Citations 2 View All Figures and Topics from this paper figure 2.1 figure 2.2 Persistence (computer science) Microsoft Outlook for Mac Social engineering (security) 216 Citations Citation Type Citation Type All Types Cites Results Cites Methods Cites Background Has PDF Publication Type Author More Filters More Filters Filters Sort by Relevance Sort by Most Influenced Papers Sort by Citation Count Sort by Recency Social Justice and the Engineering Profession: Challenging Engineering Education to Move Beyond the Technical R. Nasser, M. Romanowski Political Science 2016 5 Save Alert Research Feed Educating Engineers Under a Social Justice Perspective P. Jiménez, J. Pascual, A. Mejía Sociology, Computer Science Int. J. Eng. Pedagog. 2020 Highly Influenced PDF View 6 excerpts, cites background Save Alert Research Feed Engineering, Social Justice, and Peace: Strategies for Educational and Professional Reform Dean Nieusma Political Science 2013 12 Save Alert Research Feed Engineering Design and Social Justice: A Systematized Literature Review Morgan M. Hynes, Cristian Eduardo Vargas-Ordóñez Sociology 2020 PDF Save Alert Research Feed Canons against Cannons? Social Justice and the Engineering Ethics Imagi- nary D. Riley, Y. Lambrinidou Political Science 2015 22 PDF Save Alert Research Feed Engineering, Social Justice and Peace : A Revolution of the Heart G. Catalano, C. Baillie Political Science 2006 10 PDF View 1 excerpt, cites methods Save Alert Research Feed Social Justice in Control Systems Engineering K. Johnson, Jon A. Leydens, Barbara M. Moskal, D. Silva, Justin Stephen Fantasky Economics 2015 6 PDF Save Alert Research Feed Engineering and Social Justice: How to help students cross the threshold Jens Kabo, Richard J. F. Day, C. Baillie Sociology 2009 8 View 3 excerpts, cites background Save Alert Research Feed Social Justice: A Missing, Unelaborated Dimension in Humanitarian Engineering and Learning Through Service Jon A. Leydens, J. Lucena Engineering 2014 32 PDF Save Alert Research Feed Towards a pedagogical model of social justice in engineering education P. Jiménez, J. Pascual, A. Mejía Computer Science, Sociology ICSIE 2019 1 Highly Influenced View 8 excerpts, cites background and methods Save Alert Research Feed ... 1 2 3 4 5 ... References SHOWING 1-10 OF 110 REFERENCES SORT BYRelevance Most Influenced Papers Recency Engineers within a Local and Global Society C. Baillie Computer Science, Sociology Engineers within a Local and Global Society 2006 41 Save Alert Research Feed Engineering Ethics: Peace, Justice, and the Earth G. Catalano Computer Science, Engineering Engineering Ethics: Peace, Justice, and the Earth 2006 50 Highly Influential View 7 excerpts, references background Save Alert Research Feed Justice and the Politics of Difference I. M. Young Political Science 1990 6,148 View 2 excerpts, references background Save Alert Research Feed Witnessing and Testifying: Black Women, Religion and Civil Rights R. Ross Sociology 2003 44 Save Alert Research Feed A theology of liberation: history, politics, and salvation G. Gutiérrez Sociology 1973 698 Save Alert Research Feed Church, Charism and Power: Liberation Theology and the Institutional Church L. Boff Art 1985 79 Save Alert Research Feed Sexism and God-talk : toward a feminist theology : with a new introduction R. Ruether Sociology 1993 337 Highly Influential View 10 excerpts, references background Save Alert Research Feed A Black Theology of Liberation James H. Cone Philosophy 1970 306 View 3 excerpts, references background Save Alert Research Feed Theatre of the Oppressed A. Boal Art 1979 1,248 Highly Influential View 9 excerpts, references background and methods Save Alert Research Feed Defending the Nation J. Krige Political Science 2007 15 Save Alert Research Feed ... 1 2 3 4 5 ... Related Papers Abstract Figures and Topics 216 Citations 110 References Related Papers Stay Connected With Semantic Scholar Sign Up About Semantic Scholar Semantic Scholar is a free, AI-powered research tool for scientific literature, based at the Allen Institute for AI. Learn More → Resources DatasetsSupp.aiAPIOpen Corpus Organization About UsResearchPublishing PartnersData Partners   FAQContact Proudly built by AI2 with the help of our Collaborators Terms of Service•Privacy Policy The Allen Institute for AI By clicking accept or continuing to use the site, you agree to the terms outlined in our Privacy Policy, Terms of Service, and Dataset License ACCEPT & CONTINUE work_as2aqif6ljbxdphr6b7zyplqgm ---- Physical education, privatisation and social justice Browse Explore more content JEBD Privatisation editorial Intro.pdf (288.88 kB) Physical education, privatisation and social justice CiteDownload (288.88 kB)ShareEmbed journal contribution posted on 04.03.2015, 13:35 by John Evans, Brian Davies Physical education, privatisation and social justice Categories Medical and Health Sciences not elsewhere classified Keywords untagged History School Sport, Exercise and Health Sciences Published in Sport, Education and Society Volume 20 Issue 1 Pages 1 - 9 Citation EVANS, J. and DAVIES, B., 2015. Physical education, privatisation and social justice. Sport, Education and Society, 20 (1), pp. 1 - 9. Publisher © Taylor & Francis Version SMUR (Submitted Manuscript Under Review) Publisher statement This work is made available according to the conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International (CC BY-NC-ND 4.0) licence. Full details of this licence are available at: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/ Publication date 2015 Notes This is a Submitted Manuscript of an editorial article published in Sport, Education and Society on 26 Sep 2014, available online: http://www.tandfonline.com/10.1080/13573322.2014.942624 DOI https://doi.org/10.1080/13573322.2014.942624 ISSN 1357-3322 eISSN 1470-1243 Publisher version http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/13573322.2014.942624 Language en Administrator link https://repository.lboro.ac.uk/account/articles/9619184 Licence CC BY-NC-ND 4.0 Exports Select an optionRefWorksBibTeXRef. managerEndnoteDataCiteNLMDC Categories Medical and Health Sciences not elsewhere classified Keywords untagged Licence CC BY-NC-ND 4.0 Exports Select an optionRefWorksBibTeXRef. managerEndnoteDataCiteNLMDC Hide footerAboutFeaturesToolsBlogAmbassadorsContactFAQPrivacy PolicyCookie PolicyT&CsAccessibility StatementDisclaimerSitemap figshare. credit for all your research. work_ashvy6u3j5h7bn4w2bpxbccoii ---- LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE Volume 7, Issue 1 2012 Article 13 Asian Journal of Comparative Law LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE Md. Saiful Karim, Southern Cross University Okechukwu Benjamin Vincents Mia Mahmudur Rahim, Macquarie University Recommended Citation: Karim, Md. Saiful; Vincents, Okechukwu Benjamin; and Rahim, Mia Mahmudur (2012) "LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE," Asian Journal of Comparative Law: Vol. 7: Iss. 1, Article 13. DOI: 10.1515/1932-0205.1344 ©2012 De Gruyter. All rights reserved. Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE Md. Saiful Karim, Okechukwu Benjamin Vincents, and Mia Mahmudur Rahim Abstract This article reviews some of the roles environmental lawyers have played in ensuring environmental justice in Bangladesh. It leans on law and social movement theories to explicate the choice (and ensuing success) of litigation as a movement strategy in Bangladesh. The activists successfully moved the courts to read the right to a decent environment into the fundamental right to life, and this has had the far-reaching effect of constituting a basis for standing for the activists and other civil society organisations. The activists have also sought to introduce emerging international law principles into the jurisprudence of the courts. These achievements notwithstanding, the paper notes that litigation is not a sustainable way to institute enduring environmental protection in any jurisdiction and recommends the utilisation of the reputation and recognition gained through litigation to deploy or encourage more sustainable strategies. KEYWORDS: Environmental legal activism, law and social movements, right to a decent environment, PIL, locus standi, Bangladesh Author Notes: Md. Saiful Karim, Associate Lecturer, School of Law and Justice, Southern Cross University, Lismore, Australia. He wishes to thank Professor Abdullah-Al-Faroque for his valuable comments on an earlier draft (saiful24bd@yahoo.com). Dr. Okechukwu Benjamin Vincents, Barrister and Solicitor, Law Society of Upper Canada. Special thanks to Prof. Chris Hilson for his useful suggestions on social movements. Mia Mahmudur Rahim, PhD , Macquarie Law School, Macquarie University. Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM I. INTRODUCTION Public interest litigation (PIL) denotes litigation initiated for the protection of public interest. In this type of litigation, the aggrieved party need not be the party in the court of law; this type of litigation can be introduced by the court itself or by any member of the public. This is an example of legal activism, by which society can claim redress for an act that is not directly safeguarded by the Constitution and where the State has failed to redress it. 1 In A. B. S. K. Songh (Railway) v. Union of India, 2 the Supreme Court of India provides the cultural orientation of PIL in this region. In this case, the court clearly mentions that the current jurisprudence of this region 3 is not an individualistic Anglo-Indian model; it is broad-based and people-oriented. It has toned down the confusion regarding the locus standi, as it mentions that “the narrow concept[s] of ‘cause of action’ and ‘person aggrieved’ and ‘individual litigation’ are becoming obsolescent”. PIL took its form after the seminal judgment of the Supreme Court of India in S. P. Gupta v. Union of India. 4 Until 1994, Bangladesh had no reported PIL decided by the Supreme Court. The Bangladesh Environmental Lawyers Association (BELA) 5 brought an environmental issue in the form of a PIL before this court for the first time in this country. Dr. Mohiuddin Farooque v. Bangladesh & Others 6 was the first case of 1 Tsun Hang Tey, “Public interest Litigation in Malaysia: Executive Control and Careful Negotiation of the Frontiers of Judicial Review” in Po Jen Yap & Holning Lau, eds., Public interest Litigation in Asia (London: Routledge, 2010); Vipon Kititasnasorchai & Panat Tasneeyanond, “Thai Environmental Law” (2000) 4 S.J.I.C.L. 1; Surya Deva, “Public interest Litigation in India: a Quest to Achieve the Impossible?” in Po Jen Yap & Holning Lau, eds., Public interest litigation in Asia (London: Routledge, 2010). 2 A.I.R. SC. 298,317 (1981). 3 The Indo-Pak Sub Continent including Bangladesh and Nepal. 4 In this case, the court provides the framework of this type of litigation as follows: “[W]here a legal wrong or a legal injury is caused to a person or to a determinate class of persons by reason of violation of any constitutional or legal right or any burden is imposed in contravention of any constitutional or legal provision or without any authority of law…and such person or determinate class of persons is by reason of poverty, helplessness or disability or socially or economically disadvantaged position, unable to approach the Court of relief, any member of the public can maintain an application for an appropriate direction, order or writ”. For details, see AIR S.C. 149 (1982) at 188. 5 Established in 1992, BELA is the best known Bangladeshi NGO working with the broad objective of promoting environmental justice and contributing to the development of sound environmental jurisprudence. BELA is a member of IUCN–the World Conservation Union, Environmental Law Alliance Worldwide and the South Asian Watch on Trade, Economics and Environment. In 2003 it received the Global 500 Role of Honors of the United Nations. For details, see online: (last accessed 17 November 2011). 6 Writ Petition No. 891 of 1994. Dr. Mohiuddin Farooque was the founder of BELA. 1 Karim et al.: LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE Published by De Gruyter, 2012 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM this nature in this country. Thus, the determination of locus standi of the petitioner was the vital substantive issue to be settled. 7 In this case, the legality of an experimental structural project of the huge Flood Action Plan of Bangladesh was challenged. The High Court Division of the Supreme Court of Bangladesh 8 initially rejected the petition of this case on the grounds that the petitioner had no standing. The petitioner had preferred an appeal to the Appellate Division of the Supreme Court of Bangladesh. The Division decided the issues of locus standi in PIL. In July 1996, the Appellate Division gave its decision, in which Mustafa Kamal, J. observed: In so far as it concerns public wrong or public injury or invasion of fundamental rights of an indeterminate number of people, any member of the public, being a citizen, suffering the common injury or common invasion in common with others or any citizen or an indigenous association, as distinguished from a local component of a foreign organisation, espousing that particular cause is a person aggrieved and has the right to invoke the jurisdiction under Article 102. Since 1994, BELA, Bangladesh Legal Aid and Services Trust (BLAST), Ain o Salish Kendra (ASK), and numerous lawyers have undertaken a large number of cases that have contributed to the development of PIL in this country. To date, the PILs in this country have been due to various environmental problems; amongst these, the relief sought against pollution caused by companies is prominent. This is mainly because the environmental regulation framework and this country’s governmental agencies are either inefficient, biased, or do not have adequate strategies to tackle environmental degradation by business operations. In Bangladesh, the human right to a decent environment has been established as a fundamental right. The judicial activism that made this possible is a direct outcome of the activism of the environmental lawyers. In most of the cases, it is those lawyers that initiated the arguments that the courts took up in reaching the favourable decisions. The judges themselves have even voiced 7 Writ Petition No. 998 of 1994. 8 The Supreme Court of Bangladesh is the highest court of this country. This court is divided into two Divisions: The Appellate Division and the High Court Division. Both these divisions sit in Dhaka. The High Court Division has some original jurisdiction and it is the appellate authority of the subordinate courts. It decides all writ petitions. Against the decision of this Division, an aggrieved person can go to the Appellate Division. The decision of this Division is final. These Divisions are safeguarded by the Constitution and they provide clarification of any issues related to the constitutional provisions. For details, see Articles 94–113 of the Constitution of the Peoples’ Republic of Bangladesh. 2 Asian Journal of Comparative Law, Vol. 7 [2012], Iss. 1, Art. 13 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM appreciation of the efforts of the environmental lawyers on more than one occasion.9 However, the successes of this activism via environmental PIL still have significant problems beyond the limitations of PIL. This activism in Bangladesh often develops “policy evolution fora” for a particular national issue and influences executive governance through judicial governance in sectors highlighted by groups of public interest litigants. Along with an insufficient impact on a substantive change into the social movement, this type of overlapping in the major organs of the state illustrates some dissatisfaction with judicial process. Government efforts to control environmental legal activist organisations under NGO regulations comprise another obstacle for this activism. This hinders the entrance of other organisations into the legal activism arena. 10 Additionally, ongoing limitations in resources are continually a major bottleneck, even for well- established organisations. For instance, these organisations are in extreme shortage of legal and scientific literature on the environment. Research and publication from the social movement organisations are insufficient. Moreover, there is a dearth of supporting quality research from academia. These factors have compelled the environmental lawyers to carryout research by themselves. Nevertheless, it is very difficult for the lawyers to conduct extensive research in light of time constraints and limited funds. To compound matters, each time the environmental lawyers refer to in-house research in arguments, their positions carry less weight because the researcher himself is a party to the dispute. Sometimes, environmental organisations appear helpless in their fight against wealthy and influential parties, since litigation in Common Law courts involves a great amount of resources. Threats of death and other forms of harm are common against human rights defenders or environmental activists of developing countries, and Bangladesh is no exception. 11 Moreover, the social change motion set by the judicial activism in this country, in most cases, is less than participatory, which has (arguably) led to unrealistic solutions. There are some limitations of this activism, with respect to 9 Dr. Mohiuddin Farooque v. Bangladesh and Others, 55 DLR (HCD) 69 (2003) (hereinafter Industrial Pollution Case) at [62]; Dr. Mohiuddin Farooque v. Bangladesh and Others, 50 DLR (HCD) 84 (1998) at [83] (hereinafter FAP 20 Judgment on Merit). 10 Asian Centre for Human Rights, “Bangladesh's Offer: Become GONGOs or Be Ready for Government Takeover”, online: (last accessed 28 January 2009); Shah A.M.S. Kibria, “Farewell to the NGOs: Their Days in Bangladesh are Over?” The Daily Star (6 February 2004). 11 Amnesty International, “Bangladesh: Human Rights Defenders Under Attack”, online: (last accessed 28 January 2009). 3 Karim et al.: LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE Published by De Gruyter, 2012 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM access, effectiveness, and sustainability. These shortcomings need to be explored and addressed if the true promise of this activism is to be unleashed. Given this, the aim of the present paper is to discuss the evolution of environmental legal activists in Bangladesh – to highlight the achievements and note the challenges. In having this discussion, various analytical approaches may be adopted. However, the paper will lean on some law and social movement theories to put the Bangladesh environmental movement in perspective and explicate the adopted strategies. 12 This approach has the added advantage of providing some basis for making recommendations useful not only for Bangladeshi activists but also for other organisations that are similarly situated. The aspect of social movement theories that is the main concern in this paper is litigation as a movement strategy – particularly legal mobilisation, which helps illuminate the reasons for the choice of litigation as a movement strategy. To help locate environmental civil society organisations in Bangladesh within the social movement discourse, the remainder of the present section briefly discusses social movements generally. However, it also discusses the role of law in social movements and highlights the features of legal mobilisation theory of major concern in the context of the present study. The second section of the paper discusses the achievements of the Bangladesh environmental legal activists, particularly regarding the recognition of the right to a decent environment, the standing of some civil society organisations, and the progressive development of environmental jurisprudence in Bangladesh. The third section proceeds based on legal mobilisation and other social movement theories to discuss the choice of litigation in Bangladesh and the possible reasons for the successes seen in the achievements outlined in the second section. Section four discusses the limits of litigation, particularly PIL as a movement strategy. Section five summarises the findings of the analysis and offers predictions of future developments, opportunities, and challenges for environmental activism in relation to PIL. A. Social Movements The aim of this part is not to provide a template for determining whether or not the civil society organisations engaged in environmental legal activism in Bangladesh qualify as social movement organisations. Instead, it is to map an 12 Key questions answered by social movement theorists include “why movements originate when they do, how they attract and maintain support, how they present issues and formulate strategies and tactics, how they structure organizations, how they change cultures, why they generate opposition and sometimes decline, and how and why they succeed or fail in their objectives”, S. Staggenborg, Social Movements (Don Mills, Ont.: Oxford University Press, 2008) at 2. 4 Asian Journal of Comparative Law, Vol. 7 [2012], Iss. 1, Art. 13 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM overview of some of the views adopted by scholars on the meaning of the term. 13 As McCann noted, “considerable disagreement and uncertainty exist regarding just how the very concept of ‘social movement’ itself should be defined.” 14 Hence, the overriding considerations here are whether the activities of the organisations in focus can be explicated by reference to social movement theories and whether reference to such theories can provide useful insight, particularly regarding lessons learned from prior studies. According to Charles Tilly in Social Movements, a distinctive way of pursuing public politics began to take shape in western countries during the late 18th century, which has since spread and come to be known as social movements. Such movements combined three elements: 1) campaigns of collective claims on target authorities; 15 2) an array of claim-making performances, including special purpose associations, public meetings, media statements, and demonstrations (social movement repertoire); and 3) public representations of the causes’ worthiness, unity, number of members, and commitment. 16 In Tilly’s view, social movement campaigns involve interactions between at least three parties: “a group of self-designated claimants, some object(s) of claims, and a public of some kind.” 17 He treated the concept as a distinctive form of contentious politics. It is contentious because social movements involve collective making of claims that would conflict with someone else’s interests if realised. It is also politics, because governments of some sort figure somehow in the claim-making as either claimants, objects of the claim, allies of the objects, or monitors of the contention. 18 In Contentious Politics, Charles Tilly and Sidney Tarrow added social movement bases – the organisations, networks, traditions, and solidarities that sustain social movement activities – as a fourth element to the three elements mentioned above, and proffered a definition of social movements. 19 They defined it as “a sustained campaign of claim making, using repeated performances that 13 There are different definitions of social movements, and some of these do not even consider litigation as a social movement tactic/strategy. Given this, this article confined it within the established thoughts of social movement and judicial activism, and do not attempt to made any comparative study with the different definitions of social movement and judicial activism. 14 M. McCann, “How Does Law Matter for Social Movements” in B. Garth & A. Sarat, eds., How Does Law Matter (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1998) at 77. 15 C. Tilly, Social Movements, 1768-2004 (Boulder: Paradigm Publishers, 2004) at 4. For Tilly, authorities include government officials, property owners, religious functionaries and other whose action or inaction significantly affect the welfare of many people. 16 Ibid. at 7. 17 Ibid. at 4; “A campaign always links at least three parties: a group of self-designated claimants, some object(s) of claims, and a public of some kind…Not the solo actions of claimants, object(s), or public, but interactions among the three, constitute a social movement. (emphasis added)”. 18 Ibid. at 3. 19 C. Tilly & S. Tarrow, Contentious Politics (Boulder: Paradigm Publishers, 2007) at 8. 5 Karim et al.: LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE Published by De Gruyter, 2012 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM advertise the claim, based on organisations, networks, traditions, and solidarities that sustain these activities.” 20 This, as is to be expected, is not the only characterisation of “social movements”: many other theorists adopt descriptions that do not distinguish as strictly as Tilly’s does. Suzanne Staggenborg, for example, identified several theorists who argue that movement activity occurs in a wide range of venues and through a variety of forms of collective action. Among these, McCarthy and Zald, define social movements as “a set of opinions and beliefs in a population which represents preferences for changing some elements of the social structure and/or reward distribution of a society.” 21 While this definition more easily explains most civil society organisations that would benefit from social movement theories, one of the problems with its non-restrictive general view is that it fails to adequately differentiate social movements from minority political parties, interest groups, and other forms of collective action for purposes of analysis. This is an important point because, to put it in Tilly’s words, expansion of the term to include all sorts of popular collective action may “badly handicap any effort to describe and explain how social movements actually work”. 22 Beyond this handicap, Tilly saw little harm in such a broadening of the term in casual political discussion. 23 Notwithstanding, many theorists have sought ways to distinguish social movements from other forms of collective action. For example, McCann outlined four ingredients to delimit social movements and differentiate them from political parties and interest groups for the purpose of the introduction to his Law and Social Movements. Only three of those are necessary for our purposes here: 1) “Social movements aim for a broader scope of social and political transformation than do more conventional political activities.” 24 This means that, although social movements may press for tangible short-term goals, they are inspired by more radical visions of a different and better society. 25 2) Although social movements employ a wide range of tactics (as do parties and interest groups), social movements would tend to rely more on communicative strategies of information disclosure as well as disruptive tactics such as protests, strikes, and marches that halt or upset ongoing practices. These are sometimes combined with conventional methods, such as litigation. The emphasis here is on “disruptive”. Litigation here 20 Ibid. 21 See S. Staggenborg, Social Movements, supra note 12 at 6–7. 22 C. Tilly, Social Movements, 1768-2004, supra note 15 at 7. 23 Ibid. 24 M. McCann, “Introduction” in M. McCann, ed., Law and Social Movements (Burlington: Ashgate, 2006) at xiv. 25 Ibid. 6 Asian Journal of Comparative Law, Vol. 7 [2012], Iss. 1, Art. 13 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM serves as a platform for “rebellion” against existing structures of relations. 26 3) “Social movements tend to develop from core constituencies of non-elites whose social positions reflect relatively low degrees of wealth, prestige, or political clout.” 27 This does not mean that social movements and the elite do not mix, because “movements may find leadership or alliance among elites and powerful organisations”. 28 In sum, theorists like Tilly have favoured a narrowly delimited concept of social movement, while others like McCarthy and Zald prefer a less restrictive description, and yet others like McCann proffer a way to distinguish movements from other forms of collective action when a less restrictive definition is utilised. McCann went on to discuss legal mobilisation by social reform movements. 29 In doing so, he addressed Rosenberg’s perspective, which is a much stronger critic of judicial activism for social movement. 30 While Rosenberg questions whether judicial activism can bring about social change at all, McCann tempers the doubts by raising his argument that this activism may not do so directly, but that the symbolic and strategic values behind this activism can. 31 He built this argument on Scheingold’s perspective on the politics of rights. 32 McCann explored some theories that are deemed useful for our purposes here. Among these, legal mobilisation is one of the theories that explore the relationship between law and social movement – a brief discussion of this relationship is important to help frame the present paper. 26 Ibid. See also K. J. Fitzgerald & J. Kathleen, “Radical Social Movement Organizations: A Theoretical Model” (2000) 41(4) The Sociological Quarterly 573–592. 27 Ibid. 28 Ibid. 29 M. McCann, “Legal Mobilization and Social Reform Movements” in M. McCann, ed., Law and Social Movements (Burlington: Ashgate, 2006) at 3–32. 30 Regarding Rosengber’s perspective, see G. Rosenberg, The Hollow Hope: Can Courts Bring About Social Change? (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1991) at xii+425; G. Rosenberg, “Hollow Hopes and Other Aspirations: A Reply to Feeley and McCann” (1993) 17 Law & Soc. Inquiry 761-778; for a critique of Rosenberg’s arguments, see M. Feeley, “Hollow Hopes, Flypaper, and Metaphors” 17 Law & Soc. Inquiry 745-760. 31 McCann, Rights at Work: Pay Equity Reform and the Politics of Legal Mobilization (Chicago: Chicago University Press Ltd, 1994); M. McCann, “Reform Litigation on Trial” (1992) 4 Law & Social Movements 715–747. 32 Scheingold argues that law surfaces, at least in part, as a “myth of rights.” The myth of rights refers to the widespread assumption that 1) “litigation can evoke a declaration of rights from courts,” 2) “that it can, further, be used to assure the realization of these rights,” and 3) “that realization is tantamount to meaningful change”. In this way, the myth of rights expresses an elemental faith in the promises of constitutional government, a “faith in the political efficacy and ethical sufficiency of law as a principle of government.” For details, see S. Scheingold, The politics of Rights: Lawyers, Public Policy, and Political Change (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 2004). 7 Karim et al.: LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE Published by De Gruyter, 2012 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM 1. Law and Social Movements In Law and Social Movements, McCann noted that social scientists have paid considerable attention to the role of law, litigation, and lawyers in social movements, and that consensus on these issues has generally mirrored changes in the larger political culture. 33 “Most studies in the late 1950s and 1960s, for example, provided a generally optimistic view, emphasizing the growing accessibility of courts to long-marginalized groups such as racial minorities and the poor”. 34 Conversely, publications on the topic, prior to 2006, have presented a more pessimistic view of the utility of litigation for advancing progressive social change in a capitalist society. 35 One body of literature, mostly from the Critical Legal Studies movement, has critically analysed the ideological biases of prevailing public and private law doctrines, which tend to support the status quo power relations. 36 Another body of literature focused on the institutional limitations and trade-offs inherent in social movement litigation. These studies point out that the neediest citizens lack the resources to undertake litigation, while those who can afford it find out that it is limiting, costly, and can fragment movement-building efforts, discourage people from popular mobilisation strategies, and lead to an emphasis of judicial victory over genuine social change. 37 Nevertheless, in his search for a balanced perspective on this issue, McCann has been led to reconsider the insights of “legal mobilisation” theory. “This approach fully acknowledges that litigation alone rarely advances significant social change, but at the same time it recognizes that legal rights advocacy can in some circumstances provide a useful resource for social movement building and strategic political action.” 38 The legal mobilisation approach urged by McCann sees laws as identifiable traditions of symbolic practice. Quoting Marc Galanter, 39 McCann notes that law should be analysed more as a system of cultural and symbolic meanings instead of as a set of operative controls. Law affects people primarily through communicative symbols – threats, promises, models, persuasion, legitimacy, stigma, etc. 40 “Evaluation of how Reform litigation and other institutional activities matter thus require accounting for the variable ways that 33 Ibid. at 3. 34 Ibid. 35 Ibid. 36 Ibid. 37 Ibid. at 4. 38 Ibid. 39 M. Galanter, “Reading the Landscape of Disputes: What We Know and Don't Know (and Think We Know) about our Allegedly Contentious and Litigious Society” (1983) 31 UCLAL Rev. 4 at 127. 40 Ibid. 8 Asian Journal of Comparative Law, Vol. 7 [2012], Iss. 1, Art. 13 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM differently situated groups interpret and act on those signals sent by officials over time.” 41 Since the content and relative power of legal meaning vary among differently and unequally situated citizens, legal norms, conventions and tactical manoeuvers also vary in significance over time. It also follows that discursive strategies and institutional ploys become more significant for some types of struggles than for others. This leads to a further assumption that “law…can at once both empower and disempower variously situated social groups in different types of relations.” 42 Since law, from this viewpoint, can perpetuate status quo power relations (though it can equally provide sources of opposition and change within particular institutional terrains), the more important challenge is to “determine how and to what degree groups can work within and through these legal traditions to advance their causes.” 43 In this regard, in a social movement approach, there are two levels in which legal power can be relevant to action: 1) in shaping the overall “structure of opportunities” available to movements, and 2) in the various legal resources available to groups in their struggles. 44 As will be seen below, it is also especially regarding “opportunities” and “resource mobilisation” 45 that the kind of legal mobilisation theory advocated by McCann has been the most useful in analysing the legal activism by the environmental social movement in Bangladesh. In this paper, “environmental legal activism” refers to the effort of some members of the lawyers’ community to ensure sound environmental and ecological order by applying the legal mechanism as a tool. This includes undertaking legal action against originators of environmental pollution. The conducting of research, awareness creation, and other forms of legal assistance and advocacy are also countenanced by the term. Environmental PIL aims to 41 M. McCann, supra note 14 at 81. 42 Ibid. at 82. 43 Ibid. 44 Ibid. 45 It would be worth describing the nexus amongst “right litigation”, opportunities and resource mobilisation. Litigations for rights arose due to two sets of reasons – changes to political opportunity and the involvement of certain types of people in the political movement, specially lawyers. Political opportunity (including the justice delivery system) structure is a concept under a social movement theory known as “political process model”. In this process, resource mobilisation is a vital component. In the political process model, resource mobilisation is also called “mobilising structures” that refers to the ability of the social actors like human and organisation. This is an extended version of the thoughts of resource mobilisation within the political process model. In this article, when we refer to “structural opportunity” we usually mean this version of resource mobilisation. For details of these types of resource mobilisation, see S. M. Buechlers, Social Movement Theory: A Sociology of Knowledge Analysis in Social Movements in Advanced Capitalism: The Political Economy and Cultural Construction of Social Activism (New York: Oxford University Press, 1999); D. Adams, Political Process and the Development of Black Insurgency 1930-1970 (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1999). 9 Karim et al.: LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE Published by De Gruyter, 2012 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM ensure access to justice for all members of the society, particularly members of the marginalised segment of the society. Therefore, legal activism comprehends the entire range of manoeuvres envisaged by legal mobilisation theories, including litigation. Litigation has historically been an important component of the repertoire of claim-making strategies available to environmental movements around the world. While parts of the present paper establish that litigation has been effectively employed in Bangladesh, legal mobilisation theories form the primary basis for explicating the choice of litigation by the movement organisations and the reasons for the successes. However, other related theories that deal with the rise and fall of social movements also help to buttress the limitations of litigation and the need to highlight other activist roles such as legislative and policy advocacy. Nevertheless, legal activism is not to be confused with judicial activism, which relates to the activism of judges, although, as will be seen below, the receptiveness of the judiciary to novel environmental claims is vital to the effectiveness of litigation as a social movement strategy. Furthermore, for the purposes of this paper, the view has been adopted that “environmental justice” can be achieved through “the fair treatment and meaningful involvement of all people regardless of race, colour, national origin, or income with respect to the development, implementation, and enforcement of environmental laws, regulations, and policies.” 46 Perhaps the concept is best understood by drawing attention to “environmental injustice”: Environmental injustice occurs whenever some individual or group bears disproportionate environmental risks, like those of hazardous waste dumps, or has unequal access to environmental goods, like clean air, or has less opportunity to participate in environmental decision-making. In every nation of the world poor people and minorities face greater environmental risks, have less access to environmental goods, and have less ability to control the environmental insults imposed on them. 47 Therefore, legal activism for the prevention of environmental injustice is another way of describing the focus of this paper. The next step is to show how the foregoing theories apply to the movement in Bangladesh. 46 EPA (USA), “Environmental Justice”, online: (last accessed 27 April 2009). 47 K. Shrader-Frechette, Environmental Justice: Creating Equality, Reclaiming Democracy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002) at 3. 10 Asian Journal of Comparative Law, Vol. 7 [2012], Iss. 1, Art. 13 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM B. The Environmental Social Movement in Bangladesh The campaigns for environmental protection in Bangladesh, although varied and multifaceted, are sufficiently interlinked and sustained to meet most characterisations of “social movement”. They have even displayed all of the elements in Tilly’s restrictive characterisation of the term: collective claims, claim-making performances, and public representations of worthiness etc. The strong participants in these campaigns include, but are not limited to, the Bangladesh Centre for Advanced Studies (BCAS), the Bangladesh Poribesh Andolon (BAPA), and BELA. Since 1986, BCAS has been involved in research and publication on environmental issues. It seeks to address sustainable development through (a) environment-development integration, (b) good governance and people’s participation, (c) poverty alleviation and sustainable livelihoods, and (d) economic growth and public-private partnership. It has produced a number of publications that have influenced national environmental policymaking. 48 BCAS’s contribution to environmental conservation is recognised within and outside Bangladesh. 49 BAPA seeks to build a nationwide civic movement aimed at stopping and reversing environmental degradation in Bangladesh. It favours social mobilisation, policy advocacy, and conservation, and has organised conferences, adopted resolutions, and been involved in awareness campaigns through its publications, protests, and other activities. 50 BAPA’s contribution to the environmental movement is also acclaimed by a number of authors. 51 However, regarding environmental legal activism in Bangladesh, the oldest and most prominent of these organisations is BELA. In Tilly’s characterisation, it is the claims for a better environment, which brings these organisations together, that constitute the social movement, and not the organisations themselves. 52 Nevertheless, BELA and others engaged in litigation 48 See BCEAS, “BCAS website”, online: (last accessed 17 April 2009). 49 UNEP, “Climate Change Links 2008 Champions of the Earth Award Winners”, online: (last accessed 25 June 2009). 50 See BAPA, “BAPA website”, online: (last accessed 27 May 2009). 51 See D. A. Ahsan et al., “The Relationship of National and International Environmental NGOs in Bangladesh and Their Role in Wetland Conservation” (2009) 3 International Journal of Environmental Research 23 at 31; and N. Islam, “Broader Significance of the Environmental Movement in Bangladesh”, online: (last accessed 10 January 2009). 52 Tilly, supra note 15 at 6: (“Analysts often confuse a movement’s collective action with the organizations and networks that support the action or even consider the organizations and networks to constitute the movement…rather than the networks in which they engage”). 11 Karim et al.: LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE Published by De Gruyter, 2012 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM represent an important component of the campaigns: the litigation facet thereof. Whereas Tilly, did not countenance litigation as a social movement performance, legal mobilisation theorists like McCann do. C. Environmental Legal Activism in Bangladesh The majority of environmental protection achieved through legal activism discussed below is related to the activities of BELA. However, after the landmark judgment in the FAP-20 case (discussed below) – in which standing was allowed for environmental civil society organisations if certain conditions are present – some other human rights and legal aid organisations, including, BAPA, Bangladesh Legal Aid and Services Trust (BLAST), and Ain o Salish Kendra (ASK) began to participate in filing PILs for environmental protection. BLAST, ASK, and BELA have worked together to file a number of PILs for environmental protection. For example, both BELA and BLAST moved separate writ petitions for prevention of Vehicular Pollution in Dhaka City. 53 Additionally, BELA provides legal assistance to several other environmental organisations in filing writ petitions, some cases filed under the name of BELA were made on behalf of other environmental civil society organisations. 54 Since BELA is the only environmental civil society organisation in Bangladesh that has environmental legal advocacy as its reason for existence, it is not surprising that it has filed and won many more environmental cases than any of the others has. 55 This is why its activities and processes feature most prominently in the present analysis. Nevertheless, the road to the litigation championed by these organisations has been rife with obstacles. Bangladesh is gifted with an unparalleled natural panorama. The country is affluent in terms of natural resources and hardworking people. However, it is deficient in terms of sustainable and sound management of these environmental 53 Dr. Mohiuddin Farooque v. Bangladesh and Others, 55 DLR (HCD) 613 (2003) (hereinafter Dhaka City Vehicular Pollution Case). 54 Some of these cases are: Nijera Kori v. Bangladesh and others, Writ Petition no. 7248 of 2003 (Illegal Shrimp Cultivation); Bangladesh Environmental Lawyers Association (BELA) and Global Village, Rangamati v. Bangladesh and others, Writ Petition No. 2459 of 2004 (Construction of a Community Centre in the Sole Municipal Park of Rangamati town); Bangladesh Environmental Lawyers Association (BELA) and Thengamara Mohila Sabuj Sangha (TMSS) v. Bangladesh and others, Writ Petition No. 4244/04 (Illegal Sand Extraction from River Korota); Nijera Kori and others v. Bangladesh and others, Writ Petition No. 5194 of 2004 (Illegal Shrimp Cultivation and Settlement of Land in favour of Landless People). See BELA, “List of Public Interest Litigation”, online: (last accessed 30 January 2009). 55 BELA’s website lists 62 cases it has filed, about 43 of which have had some sort of decision. Most of the decided cases had positive outcome: online: (last accessed 29 June 2009); none of the other organisations surveyed had anything close to these numbers on environmental issues. 12 Asian Journal of Comparative Law, Vol. 7 [2012], Iss. 1, Art. 13 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM resources. 56 Historically, the law and institutions dealing with natural resources in Bangladesh were “use” oriented; they are geared towards extracting maximum economic benefit. Sometimes, this approach forecloses the interest of future generations. 57 Like other South Asian common law counterparts, the legal system of Bangladesh features an adversarial legal system of “formal procedural justice dominated by litigants of equal status engaged in adversarial processes, and provides binding, win-lose remedies”. 58 One present day result of this system is that its adversarial nature is not always attractive, and its time-consuming, expensive nature means that the civil courts are not easily accessible to those who are most affected by environmental degradation. Additionally, the emerging principles of international environmental law have been very slow in finding their way into the jurisprudence of Bangladesh’s civil courts. Given the foregoing barriers in the legal system, litigation ought not to have been a viable option for environmental protection in Bangladesh. Nevertheless, some legal practitioners considered it possible to champion environmental justice through the courts. Against this backdrop, this paper now explores the contribution of legal activism in advancing the course of the overall social movement for ensuring environmental justice in Bangladesh. The barriers that existed in the legal system help explain why the legal activists did not choose well-travelled paths in civil procedure such as the traditional writ of summons, instead using writ petitions in procedures that may be described as PIL. In Bangladesh, a civil suit starts with the presentation of a plaint (writ of summons) by the plaintiff. However, there is no scope for PIL under the Civil Procedure Code, although there is scope for class action, representative action, and action in public nuisance. Notwithstanding, as will be seen below, Article 102 of the Constitution seems to provide such a scope and has been leveraged as such through writ petitions. 59 However, this does not explain why litigation was thought desirable in the first place. The paper leans on law and social movement theories to discuss the reasons for the PIL being used, the possible reasons for the measure of success achieved so far, and the limits of PIL as a social movement strategy. First, 56 See UNEP and ESCAP, Coastal Environmental Management Plan for Bangladesh Vol. One: Summary (Bangkok: UN, 1987). 57 M. Farooque, “Regulatory Framework and Some Examples of Environmental Contamination in Bangladesh” in BELA, ed., Selected Writings of Mohiuddin Farooque (Dhaka: BELA, 2004) at 20. 58 H. E. Chodosh et al., “Indian Civil Justice System Reform: Limitation and Preservation of the Adversarial Process” (1997-1998) 30 New York University Journal of International Law and Politics 1 at 1-4. 59 For a more detailed outline of the procedural rights in the courts of Bangladesh, see J. Razzaque, Public interest environmental litigation in India, Pakistan and Bangladesh (The Hague: Kluwer Law International, 2004) at 191–193; 289–292. 13 Karim et al.: LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE Published by De Gruyter, 2012 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM however, the section below will review some of the achievements of the legal activists before discussing the reasons and limits of the litigation strategy to help illustrate the broader discussion. II. THE ACHIEVEMENTS OF THE LEGAL ACTIVISTS The present section discusses a number of the cases that established the right to a decent environment in Bangladesh, granted standing to civil society organisations, and introduced some emerging international law principles into the county’s jurisprudence. However, these cases are discussed in a way that highlights the role of the activists; the arguments they proffered are highlighted, where possible. Although the emphasis here is not on the judicial activism of the judges, there are instances where the arguments of the activists stopped and the judges went a little further in some of the cases. The section is not meant to be exhaustive. 60 A. Recognition of the Right to a Decent Environment The recognition of the right to a decent environment as a fundamental right is viewed by some as the first important step towards ensuring environmental justice for all. The legal activists in Bangladesh share this view and have sought to establish this right in Bangladesh. Although there is no specific provision in the Constitution of Bangladesh on the fundamental right to a decent environment, Articles 31 and 32 of the Constitution do guarantee the right to life. The activists broadly interpreted this right to life to include the right to a decent environment. In this regard, a series of writ petitions filed by BELA engendered some positive development. The question of the broader meaning of the right to life was raised for the first time in the case of Dr. Mohiuddin Farooque v. Bangladesh and others (Radiated Milk Case). 61 In that case, part of several consignments of skimmed milk imported by Respondent No. 6, Danish Condensed Milk Bangladesh Limited, was found, after several tests, to contain radiation levels above the minimum approved level of 95 Bq per kilogram. The petitioner, the then Secretary General of BELA, submitted to the court in a public interest Writ 60 For a more elaborate discussion of environmental PIL in Bangladesh, see ibid.; For the literature on the PIL in general in Bangladesh, see N. Ahmed, Public Interest Litigation in Bangladesh: Constitutional Issues and Remedies (Dhaka: BLAST, 1999); R. Haque, Judicial Activism in Bangladesh: A Golden Mean Approach (Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing, 2011); W. Mesnki, “Public Interest Litigation: Deliverance From all Evils” (2002) 6 Bangladesh Journal of Law 1-9; J. Cooper, “Public Interest Law Revisited” (2000) 2 (1) Bangladesh Journal of Law 1-25. 61 Dr. Mohiuddin Farooque v. Bangladesh and Others, 48 DLR (HCD) 438 (1996) (hereinafter Radiated Milk Case). 14 Asian Journal of Comparative Law, Vol. 7 [2012], Iss. 1, Art. 13 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM Petition that the consumption of food items containing radiation levels above the approved limit is a threat to the life of the people of Bangladesh, including himself. He cited Article 18 (1) of the Constitution, which requires the State to take measures to raise the level of nutrition and improve public health. He also cited Article 21 (2) of the Constitution, which enjoins public officers to strive to serve the people and noted that the activities of government officers in dealing with the consignment in question have threatened the life of the people. He thus contended that the officers in question had violated Articles 31 (right to the protection of the law) and 32 (right to life and personal liberty) of the Constitution in not compelling the importer to send back the tainted milk. 62 Kazi Ebadul Hoque, J., agreed with the petitioner and thus agreed to the extended meaning of the right to life. Thus, the right to life was construed as including a right to a decent environment. This interpretation has had far reaching effects, most notably on the question of the locus standi of environmental activists. In Dr. Mohiuddin Farooque v. Bangladesh and others (the FAP-20 Case), 63 the relationship between the right to a decent environment and locus standi came out clearly. The case was an appeal of the decision of a High Court Division of the Supreme Court (hereinafter, High Court Division) summarily rejecting a writ petition filed by the then Secretary General of BELA. 64 The Petition was brought under Article 102 of the Bangladesh Constitution; 65 however, the trial court rejected it on the grounds that the appellant is not “any person aggrieved” within the meaning of that provision. On appeal, Dr. Faroque argued, inter alia, that those whose fundamental rights are being violated need not themselves invoke the jurisdiction under Article 102 (1); others espousing their cause may do so provided the persons aggrieved do not object. He noted, “the appellant is espousing the cause of violation of Fundamental Rights of a large segment of the population in respect of their right to life, property, and vocation”. 66 In the lead judgment, Mustafa Kamal, J., agreed. He found that Article 102 (1) is “a mechanism for the enforcement of Fundamental Rights which can be enjoyed by an individual alone insofar as his individual rights are concerned, but 62 Ibid. at [4]. 63 Dr. Mohiuddin Farooque v. Bangladesh and Others, 49 DLR (AD) 1 (1997) (hereinafter FAP 20 Case). 64 From the Judgment and Order dated 18-8-94 passed by the High Court Division in Writ Petition No. 998 of 1994. 65 The Constitution of the People’s Republic of Bangladesh (As Modified up to 17 May 2004), Article 102 (1) The High Court Division on the application of any person aggrieved, may give such directions or orders to any person or authority, including any person performing any function in connection with the affairs of the Republic, as may be appropriate for the enforcement of any the fundamental rights conferred by Part III of this Constitution. 66 FAP 20 Case, supra note 63 at [25]. 15 Karim et al.: LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE Published by De Gruyter, 2012 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM which can also be shared by an individual in common with others when the rights pervade and extend to the entire population and territory.” 67 Having noted this finding, the next important question, for our purposes, is whether the protection of the environment amounts to the protection of a fundamental right. On this, His Lordship noted that the petition is concerned with an environmental issue but that there is no specific fundamental right in the constitution dealing with the environment. 68 However, he skirted the question of whether the fundamental right to life encompasses the right to a decent environment, choosing instead to rely on the averment of the appellant in making the connection between the environment and fundamental rights. However, in his concurring judgment, B. B. Roy Choudhury, J., did not shy away from making a direct connection between environmental protection and fundamental rights. This has helped the appellant getting locus standi to maintain the writ petition on their behalf. His Lordship noted that the protection and preservation of environment, ecological balance, freedom from pollution of air and water, and sanitation, without which life can hardly be enjoyed, are within the ambit of the constitution of this country. 69 In another writ petition filed by BELA to stop pollution from some ultra hazardous industries, A.B.M. Khairul Hoque J. shared the same view. He mentions that life means a “qualitative life among others, free from environmental hazards.” 70 In that case, BELA brought the action as a “person aggrieved” under Article 102 of the Constitution, with the right to life as the fundamental right that has been breached. 71 It maintained that although the Government by its own survey identified factories and industrial units that created ecological imbalance due to discharge of various industrial wastes into the air and water bodies, it has failed to implement the decision taken in the light of the survey. This, BELA contended, violated the Government’s statutory duties. 72 The court agreed. In another case, filed in connection with the failure of the government to seal tube-wells that were contaminated with arsenic, the Appellate Division of the Supreme Court recognised the connection between environmental pollution and the violation of the right to life, as well as the need to improve the natural and man-made environment with a view to protecting this right. In this case, Md 67 Ibid. at [44]. 68 Ibid. at [55]. 69 Ibid. at [102]. 70 Industrial Pollution Case, supra note 9 at [53]. 71 Ibid. at [13] and [14]. 72 Ibid. at [18]. 16 Asian Journal of Comparative Law, Vol. 7 [2012], Iss. 1, Art. 13 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM Tafazzul Islam, J., citing the decision of the Indian Supreme Court in the Virender Gaur v. State of Haryana, 73 observed that: [H]ygienic environment is an integral facet of right to healthy life, and it will be impossible to live with human dignity without a humane and healthy environmental protection. Therefore, it has now become a matter of grave concern for human existence. Promoting environment protection implies maintenance of environment as a whole comprising the man-made and natural environment. Therefore, there is a constitutional imperative of the State government and the municipalities not only to ensure and safeguard proper environment but also an imperative duty to take adequate measures to promote, protect, and improve both the man-made and the natural environment. 74 Therefore, beginning with the radiated milk case, legal activism has facilitated the recognition of the human right to a decent environment in Bangladesh. The Supreme Court interpreted the fundamental right to life liberally to include the right to a decent environment by accepting the views of activist lawyers. While the reading of the right to life to include decent environment is hardly a novel construction, having been used in India before now, for example, it is not an incontrovertible approach. Nonetheless, it may be considered vital to environmental protection in a jurisdiction like Bangladesh. 1. The Complexities of Recognising the Right to a Decent Environment by Extending the Ambit of Right to Life Some commentators have highlighted the difficulties inherent in the postulation of a substantive right to a decent environment. For example, Boyle highlighted some of the objections to this approach. He notes that “definitional problems are inherent in any attempt to postulate environmental rights in qualitative terms.” 75 The terms satisfactory, decent, viable, or healthy environment may be incapable of substantive definition. The approach by the courts of Bangladesh has not only upheld such a right, but did so by reading the right into an existing right. Regarding the correct ambit of “right to life”, the overall scheme of international human rights law may not be said to have countenanced this interpretation. Most of the instruments have separate provisions for 73 [2] SCC 577 (1995) at [7]. 74 Rabia Bhuiyan, MP v Ministry of LGRD and others, 59 DLR (AD) 176 (2007) at [25]. 75 A. Boyle, “The Role of International Human Rights Law in the Protection of the Environment” in A. Boyle & M. Anderson, eds., Human Rights Approaches to Environmental Protection (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1996) at 50. 17 Karim et al.: LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE Published by De Gruyter, 2012 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM health/standard of living/environment and the right to life. 76 For the Covenants, the right of everyone to the highest attainable standard of physical and mental health through, inter alia, the improvement of all aspects of environmental and industrial hygiene is found in the International Covenant on Economic Social and Cultural Rights(ICESCR), Article 12 (2) (a). 77 The right to life is found in the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR), Article 6. The United Nations negotiations by which these rights are provided for under separate instruments have implementation consequences. ICCPR rights are slated for immediate implementation, while ICESCR rights are intended to be implemented progressively in keeping with available resources. 78 Both Covenants were adopted at the same time, and different rights were assigned to each according to how the member States agreed they were to be implemented. Furthermore, in interpreting the right to life in Article 6 of the ICCPR, the Human Rights Committee (HRC) did not countenance environmental protection, speaking instead of killings, deprivation of life, and wars. 79 Nevertheless, it would be quite difficult to argue that the judicial decisions requiring the sealing of tube wells contaminated with arsenic and preventing the distribution of milk tainted with unacceptable levels of radiation, as seen in the above cases, does not protect the right to life. However, when it comes to the discharge of various industrial wastes into the air and water bodies, as also seen in one of the above cases, it becomes questionable as to whether the right to be protected from such pollution quite reaches the threshold of a non-derogable right. According to the HRC, the right to life is “the supreme right from which no derogation is permitted even in times of public emergency.” 80 This is more so given that there may be real technical and/or financial constraints to the enforcement of adequate pollution standards. In short, the reinterpretation of the right to life to include the right to a decent environment will not always be a perfect fit; it would sometimes lead to open-ended obligations that would inordinately stretch state resources, particularly in a developing country like Bangladesh. However, for the purposes of the present paper, it must be ascertained whether it was necessary to couch the claim for a decent environment 76 See e.g., UN General Assembly, Universal Declaration of Human Rights, 10 December 1948, 217 A (III): provides for the right to life under Article 3 and the right to a standard of living adequate for health and wellbeing in Article 25. 77 International Covenant on Economic Social and Cultural Rights, 1966 (ICESCR), 16 December 1966, 993 UNTS 3 (entered into force 3 January 1976), Art. 12. 78 See Arts. 2 ICCPR, 1966 and ICESCR, 1966. 79 CCPR, CCPR General Comment No. 6 The Right to Life, 30 April 1982, online: (last accessed 28 April 2009). 80 Ibid., para. 1. 18 Asian Journal of Comparative Law, Vol. 7 [2012], Iss. 1, Art. 13 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM in the language of rights and, if so, whether the right to life was the only viable option. Bangladesh is a party to most of the major international environmental conventions. 81 However, the country is very slow in enacting domestic laws to implement the treaties. Accordingly, the presence of a social movement for environmental justice is not surprising. It is equally unsurprising that the activists chose to frame their claims in the language of rights, because traditionally, the language of rights have proved effective in rallying people to social movement causes around the world. According to McCann, an acknowledged manifestation of legal mobilisation in reform politics is its contribution to movement building. This building process is made up of two related aspects: the development of an agenda of rights-based claims, and mass constituent activation and organisation based on the rights claims. 82 Citing Elizabeth Schneider, McCann noted that agenda building around particular rights claims can emerge in a number of ways, including by exploiting the conflict between settled rights claims and practices that violate those rights, by exploiting contradictions within discursive logics of rights, or by developing logical extensions or new applications of already settled rights claims. 83 The extent of the contribution of the establishment of the right to a decent environment to the building of the environmental movement in Bangladesh, and some of the conditions that would have informed litigation as a movement strategy are explored below. However, at this juncture, it suffices to posit that the activists actually developed their rights-based claim by insisting on a logical extension to the right to life. Given the difficulties associated with a substantive right to a decent environment and the shortcoming of retrofitting the right to life to accommodate environmental claims, did the activists have options other than extending the meaning of the right to life? As will be seen below, the standing of the activists to bring environmental claims on behalf of people who are unable to represent themselves was contingent on there having been a breach of a fundamental right. Part III of the Constitution of Bangladesh does not contain any environmental rights; thus, the right to life would seem to be the only option with a chance of success, particularly in light of the successful extension of its ambit to include environmental claims in India. 84 Therefore, it would seem that the 81 Department of Environment, List of Environment Related International Conventions, Protocols, Treaties Signed/Ratified by Bangladesh, online: (last accessed 28 April 2009). 82 M. McCann, supra note 29 at 10. 83 Ibid. at 10–11. 84 See generally; Damodhar Rao v. Municipal Corporation, Hyderabad (AIR 1987 AP 170); L. K. Koolwal v. State of Rajasthan (AIR 1988 Raj 2); V. Lakshmipathy v. State of Karnataka (AIR 1992 Kant 57); Chetriya Pardushan Mukti Sangarsh Samiti v. State of UP (AIR 1990 SC 2060); 19 Karim et al.: LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE Published by De Gruyter, 2012 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM activists had few options if they were to pursue a litigation strategy. Whether or not the status quo should be maintained in this regard is a different question altogether. Without doubt, it would be more desirable for any jurisdiction to develop laws, policies, and an enforcement climate that upheld wholesome environmental protection beyond court-mediated settlements. In light of this, litigation as a movement strategy will also be explored below. 85 First, however, the following subsection will discuss how the activists achieved locus standi and sought to incorporate emerging international environmental principles into the jurisprudence of Bangladeshi courts. B. Locus Standi As is the case in many other jurisdictions, one of the initial problems encountered by the environmental legal activists was that of locus standi. The surmounting of this problem represents one of the strongest contributions of the environmental legal activists to the cause of environmental justice in Bangladesh. In the FAP-20 Case 86 discussed above, the Appellate Division of the Supreme Court paved the way for locus standi for environmental activists and other civil society organisations. It interpreted the constitutional term, “person aggrieved”, to allow BELA, represented by Dr. Mohiuddin Farooque, to file a writ petition under Article 102 of the Constitution on behalf of the people affected by a government flood mitigation pilot project. The project is known as the Compartmentalisation Pilot Project (CPP) under the Flood Action Plan (FAP) Number 20. As noted above, the High Court Division summarily rejected BELA’s Writ Petition as it was of the opinion that neither Dr. Farooque nor BELA was directly affected by the project and, consequently, did not constitute a “person aggrieved”, under Article 102 of the Constitution. The restrictive interpretation of this constitutional provision by the High Court Division was overturned on appeal by the Appellate Division of the Supreme Court, granting standing to Dr. Farooque. On this issue, Mostafa Kamal, J., held that: [I]nterpreting the word ‘any person aggrieved’ meaning only and exclusively individuals and excluding the consideration of people as a collective and consolidated personality will be a stand taken against the Constitution. 87 Subhash Kumar v. State of Bihar (AIR 1991 SC 420); Virendra Gaur v. State of Haryana 2 SCC 577 (1995). 85 According to McCann, “Legally constituted ways of doing carry with them their own limitations, biases, and burdensome baggage.” McCann, supra note 29 at 6. 86 FAP 20 Case, supra note 63. 87 FAP 20 Case, supra note 63at [47]. 20 Asian Journal of Comparative Law, Vol. 7 [2012], Iss. 1, Art. 13 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM B.B. Roy Choudhury, J., went further, and held that: The expression ‘person aggrieved’ means not only any person who is personally aggrieved but also one whose heart bleeds for his less fortunate fellow beings for a wrong done by the Government or a local authority in not fulfilling its constitutional or statuary obligations. 88 BELA’s achievement in moving the courts to grant standing to an environmental civil society organisation for the first time is particularly significant considering the history of standing in Bangladeshi courts prior to the decision. Perhaps the first case in which the question of locus standi was addressed in Bangladesh is Kazi Moklesur Rahman v. Bangladesh and another. 89 In that case, the petitioner challenged the Delhi Treaty on the grounds that its terms involved the cession of part of the territory of Bangladesh. Although the writ petition was summarily dismissed by both the High Court Division and the Supreme Court on appeal, the Supreme Court observed that the appellant had the competency to claim a hearing. 90 The Supreme Court found that the fact that the appellant was not a resident of the region of Bangladesh affected by the treaty did not preclude his competency to bring the claim. This competency is based on the threat to the appellant’s fundamental freedom of movement in the entire territory of Bangladesh. The court referred to this as a constitutional issue of grave importance. 91 This liberal view notwithstanding, this case gives no authority for standing for a person whose own fundamental right has not been infringed, such as an environmental civil society organisation not claiming redress on its own behalf. Moreover, some other locus standi cases involving associations of persons that came after this case did not meet with success. In Bangladesh Sangbad Patra Parishad, 92 it was found that the petitioner could not maintain the petition in a representative capacity. This ruling was cited with approval in Dada Match Workers Union, 93 where it was held that a trade union cannot maintain an application under Article 102 of the Constitution asking relief for its members. The court observed that the petitioner was not espousing the cause of a downtrodden and deprived section of the society that cannot afford to enforce its fundamental rights. 88 Ibid. at [97]. 89 26 DLR (SC) 44 (1974). 90 Ibid. at [17] and [18]. 91 Ibid. at [18]. 92 Bangladesh Sangbadpatra Parishad (BSP) v Bangladesh 43 DLR (AD) 126 (1991) at [12]. 93 Dada Match Workers Union v Bangladesh 29 DLR (HCD) 188 (1977). 21 Karim et al.: LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE Published by De Gruyter, 2012 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM Nevertheless, in Retired Government Employees, 94 the High Court Division held that the petitioner was a “person aggrieved” within the meaning of Article 102 (1) and (2) of the Constitution. It found that the association had an interest in ventilating the common grievances of all its members. Again, this ruling is no authority for standing for a person whose own fundamental right has not been infringed. However, in the FAP 20 Case, just such a petitioner was granted standing, not least because BELA declined to let the extant legal position deter it from pursuing environmental justice. The fact that BELA was championing the cause of the downtrodden and the seriousness of the fundamental right to life, which encompasses the right to a decent environment, informed the court’s decision in that case. The judgment not only opened the door to writ petitions for safeguarding environmental rights, but also for ensuring all other fundamental rights. C. Progressive Development of Environmental Jurisprudence Law informs societal actions and cultures such that judicial pronouncements seem to be one way to introduce internationally recognised environmental principles into the national discourse in a jurisdiction where official endorsement and application is slow. A survey of decided cases in Bangladesh reveals that the activists shared this view, because one of the consequences of the sort of legal activism discussed in the foregoing paragraphs is the development of the environmental jurisprudence of Bangladesh, including, in particular, the recognition of emerging international environmental laws and norms in the domestic arena. The international environmental law norms that the activists have sought to implement in Bangladesh include Intergenerational Equity, the Polluter Pays Principle, and the Precautionary Principle. 95 These they sought to highlight through PIL as well as legislative advocacy; however, the response from the judiciary has been mixed at best. The Bangladesh Supreme Court mentioned intergenerational equity on some occasions but has generally not been supportive of the principle, though there are signs that this attitude is changing. However, the High Court Division adopted a slightly different view in a recently decided case filed by BAPA. In Bangladesh Paribesh Andolon and another v Bangladesh and others, Imman Ali, J., observed that the “right to have open space, parks, waterbodies, etc. are rights accruing to Nature and the Environment, which it is 94 Bangladesh Retired Government Employees Welfare Association v Bangladesh 46 DLR (HCD) 426 (1994) at [21]. 95 On implementation of these international environmental law principles in Bangladesh, see generally, Razzaque, Public interest environmental litigation in India, Pakistan and Bangladesh, supra note 59, at 333–73. 22 Asian Journal of Comparative Law, Vol. 7 [2012], Iss. 1, Art. 13 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM the bounden duty of the State to preserve for the sake of future generations. [emphasis added]” 96 This case equally heralded a new direction for environmental jurisprudence in Bangladesh. A group of environmental activists challenged the legality of construction of residences for the Speaker and Deputy Speaker within the National Assembly Area through alteration of the original plan of the National Assembly Complex. The complex is recognised as a masterpiece: the work of a globally renowned architect, Louis Isadore Kahn, which is regarded as one of the best monuments of International Architectural Modernism. The court prohibited any kind of change in the original plan of the complex.97 It directed the government to consider declaring the complex a National Heritage Site and to apply to UNESCO to declare it a World Heritage Site in order to protect it from further defacement. 98 This judgement could result in the application of the terms of the World Cultural and Natural Heritage Convention 99 in Bangladesh, and perhaps pave the way for its implementation in the country. The Supreme Court also indirectly recognised the “Precautionary Principle” when it recognised the rights of potential consumers in the Radiated Milk Case. 100 Additionally, in one of the more recent cases filed by BELA, the Supreme Court directed government authorities to make necessary rules and regulations so that no hazardous ships can enter the territorial waters of Bangladesh for breaking purposes. It reasoned that the breaking of ships with hazardous substances may cause significant harm to the coastal and marine environment of the country. 101 This, indeed, is a tacit precautionary approach to environmental protection. Furthermore, in one of the writ petition cases now pending for further hearing in the High Court Division, government authorities were directed to undertake investigation to identify and measure the areas within a pristine island, Sonadia, where shrimp cultivation/forest clearing is taking place or has taken place. The government is also to list those who are involved in such cultivation/clearing and the enabling arrangements; assess, in monetary terms, the loss of forest resources for such individual shrimp cultivation/forest clearing; and 96 Bangladesh Paribesh Andolon and another v Bangladesh and others 58 DLR (HCD) 441 (2006) at [28]. 97 Ibid. at [29]. 98 Ibid. at [34]. 99 Convention Concerning the Protection of the World Cultural and Natural Heritage, 1972, 23 November 1972, 1037 UNTS 151 (entered into force 15 December 1975). 100 Radiated Milk Case, supra note 61. See Razzaque, Public interest environmental litigation in India, Pakistan and Bangladesh, supra note 59, at 357–58. 101 Bangladesh Environmental Lawyers Association (BELA) v. Bangladesh and others, Writ Petition No. 3916 of 2006, judgment delivered on 6 July 2006, unreported (hereinafter MT Alfaship Case) at 4. 23 Karim et al.: LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE Published by De Gruyter, 2012 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM submit a report to the court within two months. 102 The activists’ hope is that the court will apply the polluter pays principle. In yet another Writ Petition, also related to commercial shrimp cultivation, the High Court Division issued a Rule Nisi, calling upon the respondents to show cause as to why they should not be directed to compensate the affected people for the loss suffered by them due to the flow of saline water over their lands. 103 The activists also hope that the Supreme Court would consider these pending cases from a different viewpoint by positively responding to their arguments and, thereby, play an instrumental role in implementing emerging international environmental law norms in Bangladesh. While intergenerational equity, the precautionary principle, and the polluter pays principle may not be said to have become firmly established legal norms in Bangladesh, these dicta represent important strides in the right direction. III. WHY LITIGATION This part of the paper considers not only why litigation was considered viable in Bangladesh but also why it was successful. The theories considered apply by implication to other countries that bear certain similarities to Bangladesh. Some legal mobilisation theorists take the view that it is the direct effect (i.e., the short- term remedial reliefs) of formal legal action that motivates the choice of litigation as a strategy. 104 However, McCann urges an approach to legal mobilisation that also considers the indirect effects of official legal action on social struggles. These may include “catalysing movement building efforts, generating public support for new rights claims, or providing pressure to supplement other political tactics.” 105 In addition to the agenda development already discussed above (section II(A)(1)), forms of constituent activation discussed by McCann include publicity, rights consciousness, and political identity. 106 In Bangladesh, some of the cases discussed above attracted extensive media attention, most of which was positive. Therefore, it is not surprising that environmental questions have gained increased prominence in the national discourse. While it is difficult to measure the overall effect of the cases on mass constituent activation and the growth of the environmental movements, signs of these are available. BELA, for one, has grown from a few activists to a staff of nearly 60 people in six different offices around the country. The publicity 102 Bangladesh Environmental Lawyers Association (BELA) v. Ministry of Land and others, Writ Petition no. 4286 of 2003. 103 Gaurang Proshad Roy and Bangladesh Environmental Lawyers Association (BELA) v. Bangladesh and others, Writ Petition No. 5732 of 2005. 104 M. McCann, supra note 29 at 8. 105 Ibid. 106 Ibid. at 11–15. 24 Asian Journal of Comparative Law, Vol. 7 [2012], Iss. 1, Art. 13 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM spawned by the successful cases and the various awards bestowed on BELA and its leaders 107 have arguably added a layer of legitimacy to the environmental cause. The high success rate of the litigations also adds some persuasiveness or pressure to supplement other political tactics. Thus, legal activism yields not only direct results in terms of court ordered reliefs, but also indirect effects that support other movement strategies. Given the networking amongst the social movement organisation in Bangladesh, it is believed that these effects are felt to varying degrees in other organisations that are not directly involved in litigation. The foregoing throws some light on the advantages of litigation as a social movement strategy; however, it fails to fully answer the questions of why the activists considered litigation an option in the first place and why it has had the measure of success explained above. Some social movement scholars have developed theories that help outline the conditions that inform the choice of litigation from a social movement’s repertoire of actions. McCann outlined two of these theories: resource mobilisation and structural opportunities. 108 A. Resource Mobilisation According to McCann, scholars have a wide range of approaches to resource mobilisation, but they tend to elevate two types of concerns. “One is the focus on a pre-existing core of activist leaders who serve as the primary ‘agents of rights mobilisation’”. 109 Here, an existing core of activists may use litigation to mobilise a mass constituency. A second category of resources “includes various pre- existing organisational ties among mobilizable constituencies.” 110 Here, the theory is that organisations that are able to network with others on whom they can depend for resources such as personnel and money are more likely than previously unaffiliated persons to succeed in rights-oriented actions. The professional and educational backgrounds of social movement organisation participants form part of the resources available to an organisation, according to Hilson. Of interest to present purposes, he notes, “litigation is also only likely to be adopted as a strategy where an individual within an SMO [Social Movement Organisation] or its network has direct experience of the law.” 111 These theories are certainly borne out by the legal mobilisation story of Bangladesh. BELA was established in 1992 with Dr. Mohiuddin Farooque (1954– 107 In 2003, BELA became a laureate of the UNEP Global 500 Role of Honour, See UNEP, Adult Award Winner in 2003, online: (last accessed 9 May 2009. 108 McCann, supra note 29 at 18. 109 Ibid. 110 Ibid. 111 C. Hilson, “New Social Movements: the Role of Legal Opportunity” (2002) 9 Journal of European Public Policy 238 at 240–241. 25 Karim et al.: LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE Published by De Gruyter, 2012 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM 1997) as its founder and executive director and a group of young lawyers as founding members. The first petition by a national NGO with environmental protection consequences was filed by BELA in 1994. 112 From the very beginning, BELA has been a member of the Coalition of Environmental NGOs (CEN) in Bangladesh. 113 CEN is a loose coalition of environmental NGOs involving both lawyer- and non-lawyer-led NGOs. While CEN may not be said to be very active, it is likely that just the sense of belonging to such an umbrella organisation would, at the very least, act as moral support for emerging organisations. It is also likely that, at inception, BELA had encouragement and ideas from fellow members. In any case, it is clear that BELA was funded by pre-existing organisations. The Asia Foundation, for example, intimates that it had a meeting with Dr. Farooque in the spring of 1993 in which the details of its first grant to BELA was shaped. 114 This was before BELA filed its first petition. 115 In sum, the availability of resources is part of the reason that litigation was chosen in Bangladesh, and it played no small role in its relative success. B. Structural Opportunity In McCann’s view, structural opportunities pertain to changes in social relations experienced over time by particular groups of citizens. These could be changes related to economic depression, work roles, or new forms of state control that bring new forms of hardship and oppression. Such changes may also unsettle expectations and open new vistas of perceived opportunity or sense of entitlement. One shortcoming in this view is that it relies heavily on some of the “classical theories of the 1960s and early 1970s [which] emphasized the role of discontent or grievances in explaining the emergence of social movements”. 116 Some theorists have deemphasised this view. McCarthy and Zald, for example, pointed to some empirical work that casts doubt on the assumption of a close link 112 Dr. Mohiuddin Farooque v. Election Commission and others, Writ Petition No. 186/1994 (Nuisance during Election Campaign) 113 BELA also relates with international alliances like IUCN-the World Conservation Union, Friends of the Earth International and Environmental Law Alliance Worldwide (E-LAW). 114 K. McQuay & S. Kabir, “Reflecting on Rizwana Hasan’s Goldman environmental Prize”, online: (last accessed 1 May 2009). 115 To date, BELA has received financial assistance from a number of organisations including the Government of Bangladesh, Canadian International Development Agency, United Nations Development Programme and Manusher Jonno Foundation. 116 Hilson, “New Social Movements: the Role of Legal Opportunity”, supra note 111, at 240. 26 Asian Journal of Comparative Law, Vol. 7 [2012], Iss. 1, Art. 13 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM between preexisting discontent and generalised beliefs in the rise of social movement phenomena. 117 Without doubt, legal mobilisation could be precipitated by previously unexploited opportunity that has always been there. In this regard, a more general theory of political opportunity is more suitable to analysing the choice of litigation in Bangladesh. The approach taken by Chris Hilson in discussing “political opportunity” is particularly helpful for our purposes. Hilson drew attention to the structural and contingent components of opportunity. Structural opportunity refers to the structural openness or “closedness” of a political system, while contingent opportunity refers to the contingent receptiveness of political elites to collective action. 118 In this respect, attention must be paid to not only the openness in terms of access to the administration but also to the political receptivity to the claims being made. Hilson further noted that “litigation or protest may arise from lack of success in conventional political arena[s]”; access, though necessary, is not sufficient for success, as political elites must also be receptive to the claims being made and be willing to change policy accordingly. 119 In the Bangladesh experience, BELA cites environmental degradation through “faulty policy priorities and approaches and of course poor governance that also accounts for non-implementation of environmental laws” 120 as the backdrop for its emergence as a legal advocacy group. As noted above, some environmental protection NGOs, such as BCAS, preceded BELA; nevertheless, BELA still claimed faulty policy priorities and approaches at its inception. This indicates a measure of lack of success of the environmental movement in the conventional political arena. Furthermore, Hilson demonstrated a distinction between the broader political opportunity and the narrower legal opportunity, which theorists are wont to subsume under political opportunity. Legal opportunity relates to opportunities in court-based litigation strategy. The structural side of legal opportunity refers to the more stable features of a system, such as access to justice and standing, while the key contingent feature is judicial receptivity to policy arguments. 121 Contingent legal opportunity perhaps accounts for the actual courtroom successes of the legal activists in Bangladesh, as seen in the cases discussed above. It touches on the judicial activism of the Bangladeshi bench and the receptiveness of the judges to the claims of the activists. This helps account for not only the initial 117 J. McCarthy & M. Zald, “Resource Mobilization and Social Movement: A Partial Theory” in J. Goodwin & J. Jasper, eds., Social Movements (London: Routledge, 2007) at 33. 118 Hilson, “New Social Movements: the Role of Legal Opportunity”, supra note 111, at 242. 119 Ibid. 120 The Access Imitative, BELA, online: (last accessed 4 November 2012). 121 Hilson, “New Social Movements: the Role of Legal Opportunity”, supra note 111, at 243. 27 Karim et al.: LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE Published by De Gruyter, 2012 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM choice and success of the litigation strategy, but also for its continued employment in the movement. Judicial activism is one of those terms that defy easy definition, and this paper is not well positioned to explore the concept in any extensive manner. However, placing reliance on parts of the multidimensional model proffered by Cohen and Kremnitzer, it is not difficult to see that the major decisions that the Bangladesh legal activists would consider successful involved some judicial activism. Cohen and Kremnitzer had three visions of judicial activism, one of which hinges on the traditional vision of the judiciary. Although this vision does not fully address the various ways in which courts can impact upon society, it suffices for the purposes of the present paper. Under this approach, “activist courts are activist when they change the law, overstep their role of dispute resolution, and decide on policy and other broad social questions.” 122 Cohen and Kremnitzer discussed twelve parameters against which particular decisions may be measured to determine the level of activism of a court. Some of these indicate a measure of activism in the cases discussed above. For example, the second of the parameters concerns interpretation and holds that a court that interprets a legal text in possible contradiction with assumed original intent or its linguistic meaning is more activist than one that sticks to the original meaning. 123 As noted above, the meaning the courts assigned to the “right to life” is not one that is countenanced in the scheme of international human rights law. It is also unlikely that the framers of the Constitution had that meaning in mind. According to the fifth parameter, courts that are ready to jump threshold hurdles such as standing are generally more activist. 124 This, again, is exactly the line the courts chose to tow in response to the arguments of the legal activists on standing for environmental civil society organisations in Bangladesh. Finally, according to the ninth parameter, a court that extensively relies on foreign arrangements that are not binding in the domestic sphere would be more activists than one that does not. On the face of the cases discussed above the courts overtly relied on the outcome in the Indian courts only in a few of the cases. However, there is no gainsaying the fact that Indian jurisprudence influenced the receptiveness of the Bangladeshi judges to the environmental claims of the activists on the right to life and standing, not least because of the similarity in the outcomes. All these amount to ripe legal opportunity; an activist judiciary that is amenable to particular rights claims is always a legal opportunity for any social movement that champions such claims. This explains the continued use of litigation by the environmental social movement in Bangladesh. 122 M. Cohen & M. Kremnitzer, “Judicial Activism: A Multidimensional Model” (2005) 18 Can. J.L. & Jur. 333 at 336. 123 Ibid. at 341. 124 Ibid. at 342. 28 Asian Journal of Comparative Law, Vol. 7 [2012], Iss. 1, Art. 13 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM The foregoing notwithstanding, the use of litigation as a social movement strategy has limitations, and it is to these we turn in the following section. IV. THE LIMITS OF LITIGATION AS A MOVEMENT STRATEGY A. To PIL or Not to PIL So far, the paper has discussed the use of PIL as a social movement strategy in Bangladesh and considered the reason for the choice of litigation and why it has been successful. However, the choice of litigation as a movement strategy does seem to bring limitations. As noted above, McCann acknowledged that “litigation alone rarely advances significant social change.” 125 However, he also recognised that legal rights advocacy can, in some circumstances, provide a useful resource for social movement building, as has been demonstrated above. Regarding the use of litigation in environmental activism, some commentators have highlighted the shortcomings of PIL in particular, especially in India. 126 According to Rajamani, “[a]lthough the Court has done and continues to do exemplary work, the exercise of public interest environmental jurisdiction raises concerns with respect to access, participation, effectiveness and sustainability, concerns which need to be explored and addressed if the true promise of public interest jurisdiction is to be unleashed.” 127 In their article, The Delhi Pollution Case: the Supreme Court of India and the Limits of Judicial Power, Armin Rosencranz and Michael Jackson noted that The Supreme Court ruling to mandate the conversion of the Delhi bus fleet to CNG in M.C. Mehta v Union of India 128 was a well-informed and logical decision. Notwithstanding, they pointed to some disadvantages of the strong stance taken by the court in that case, and concluded that “the Court's action [mandating the conversion of the Delhi bus fleet to CNG] seems likely to impede capacity building in the pollution control agencies, and thereby to compromise the development of sustained environmental management in India.” 129 125 McCann, supra note 29 at 4. 126 See A. Rosencranz & M. Jackson, “The Delhi Pollution Case: The Supreme Court of India and the Limits of Judicial Power” (2003) 28 Colum. J. Envtl. L. 223. (Demonstrates with the Delhi Pollution case how litigation would not always provide long term environmental protection); L. Rajamani, “Public Interest Environmental Litigation in India: Exploring Issues of Access, Participation, Equity, Effectiveness and Sustainability” (2007) 19 J. Envtl. L. 293. (Highlights the limitations and other concerns that arise from the exercise of public interest environmental jurisdiction in Indian courts). 127 Rajamani, “Public Interest Environmental Litigation in India: Exploring Issues of Access, Participation, Equity, Effectiveness and Sustainability”, supra note 126 at 295–296. 128 S.C. Writ Pet. (Civil), M.C. Mehta v Union of India (1985) (No. 13029/1985). 129 A. Rosencranz & M. Jackson, “The Delhi Pollution Case: The Supreme Court of India and the Limits of Judicial Power”, supra note 126 at 253–254. 29 Karim et al.: LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE Published by De Gruyter, 2012 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM According to G.L. Peiris, “PIL represents a daring, and in some respects unique, response to a problem of unparalleled proportions. The character and degree of the challenge are related to societal conditions in the subcontinent, which pose the danger of significant alienation of a large section of the community from the values infusing the legal system.” However, the vigour and novelty of this judicial initiative have led to intractable dilemmas regarding the relationship between the judiciary and other organs of government. At the centre of the problem is the political accountability of the courts and, perhaps, the practicality of their leadership roles in the formulation and implementation of broad social policy. 130 In the body of this piece, Peiris referred to several heterodox features of PIL, including the tendency of the courts to get embroiled in the most controversial and divisive of policy issues; 131 detailed administrative adjudication; and fact-finding mechanisms including the appointment of committees of experts bestowed with extensive powers of discovery. 132 Some of these concerns are quite instructive and are briefly considered below regarding Bangladesh. A full consideration of the concerns is not possible in the present paper, so only brief comments are offered. Nevertheless, it should be noted from the outset that the paper considers that although a considerable amount of flexibility attaches to PIL in most developing-country jurisdictions, PIL as a procedure of litigation should not be viewed as insuperably problematic, nor should explored solutions include the abrogation of the procedure. This is particularly so when the entire gamut of PIL jurisdiction is considered, especially the human rights jurisdiction. Commentary on the exercise of PIL jurisdiction in India, for example, ranges from opposition to appreciation of the role of the court in achieving social justice. 133 Hence, the criticism outlined above notwithstanding, there is no shortage of extenuation commentaries on the exercise of PIL jurisdiction in India. For example, on the relegation of locus standi rules to allow PIL, Peiris observed that “[at] the core of the concern consistently shown by Indian courts for fostering PIL in the conditions of contemporary life in the subcontinent, is candid recognition that, in the absence of innovative mechanisms of this nature, substantive rights central to human dignity cannot but assume an illusory character in the eyes of large sections of the population.” 134 On the question of direct judicial involvement in controversial policy issues, including the 130 G.L. Peiris, “Public Interest Litigation in the Indian Subcontinent: Current Dimensions” (1991) 40 International and Comparative Law Quarterly 66 at 89. 131 Ibid. at 72. 132 Ibid. at 75–80. 133 Madhav Khosla, “Addressing Judicial Activism in the Indian Supreme Court: Towards an Evolved Debate” (2009) 32 Hastings Int’l & Comp. L. Rev. 55 at 55–56. 134 Peiris, supra note 130 at 70. 30 Asian Journal of Comparative Law, Vol. 7 [2012], Iss. 1, Art. 13 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM preservation of the environment, the author explored the problem, noted some redeeming features, and opined that “[on] the whole, then, the assessment of priorities by Indian courts is empirical and shows sensitivity to contextual factors.” 135 On the question of fact-finding committees/commissions, Vijayashri Sripati noted that most of the petitioners in PIL cases were public-spirited individuals or organisations who, due to limited resources, found it onerous to establish or prove violations of rights by states. This was the impetus of the courts in forming the commissions to aid the litigants in the expensive task of fact finding. 136 In Bangladesh, PIL for environmental justice is principally a procedure engendered by the interplay of Articles102 and 32 of the Constitution. This makes PIL primarily a fundamental rights enforcement procedure, whereby certain stringent procedural hurdles are relaxed. Although barriers are somewhat more relaxed in PIL procedures, one is not to suppose that there are no other barriers to entry to the effect that frivolous actions would ensue. As seen in the FAP 20 Case, representation of those who cannot represent themselves would seem to be a pre-requisite. 137 Although standing has been gained for environmental civil society organisations, in his concurring judgment in the FAP-20 Case, Latifur Rahman, J., noted, “that any application filed by an individual, group of individuals, associations and social activists must be carefully scrutinized by the court itself to see as to whether the petitioner has got sufficient and genuine interest in the proceeding to focus a public wrong or public injury.” 138 The test of “sufficient and genuine interest”, therefore, still subsists in Bangladesh, notwithstanding the granting of standing to social groups. 139 Furthermore, from our discussion of resource mobilisation above, it is clear that not every organisation would be able to employ PIL as a movement strategy. In the light of the current enforcement climate for environmental laws and policies in Bangladesh, to argue against PIL in broad terms and recommend further procedural restriction of access to the courts would seem difficult to support. Nevertheless, some of the questions raised on the manner in which the courts have chosen to exercise their powers in PIL cases deserve further discussion as they relate to Bangladesh. In particular, the questions of access, participation, 135 Ibid. at 75. 136 Vijayashri Sripati, “Human Rights in India-Fifty Years after Independence” (1997) 26 Denver Journal of International Law and Policy 93 at 121. 137 FAP 20 Case, supra note 63, at [97]; Dada Match Workers Union, supra note 93. 138 FAP 20 Case, supra note 63 at [86]. 139 See also Razzaque, Public interest environmental litigation in India, Pakistan and Bangladesh, supra note 59, at 292: “As the Constitution [of Bangladesh] suggested the ‘aggrieved person’ test, the court is hesitant to ignore this test altogether. Rather, they have interpreted it within the framework of the ‘aggrieved person’ test with all the flavour of the ‘sufficient interest’ test.” 31 Karim et al.: LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE Published by De Gruyter, 2012 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM effectiveness and sustainability pointed out by Rajamani, and Armin Rosencranz and Michael Jackson, are pertinent. 1. Effectiveness Regarding effectiveness, Rajamani notes that “[a]lthough the Court’s environmental commitment is seldom challenged, its ability to devise effective solutions to the problems under consideration is often called into question.” 140 In the first place, given the other issues raised in that paper (such as sustainability) perhaps the courts should not go as far as devising solutions rather than reaching decisions that point administrators in the right direction. However, if the issue is whether the decisions have been effective in protecting the environment, one would have to consider the short term direct effects and reliefs in the decisions, and the long term indirect effects of the decisions. In Bangladesh, regarding the short-term reliefs and their implementation, the environmental legal activists have had mixed results. In some instances, they were successful in not only eliciting favourable court decisions, but also in securing positive responses from the government in the implementation of the judicial decisions. A good example is the Dhaka City Vehicular Pollution Case. 141 Dhaka, the capital of Bangladesh, is one of the most polluted cities in the world. Many vehicles in Dhaka city used leaded petroleum and contributed to the emission of lead-laced gases. To save the city dwellers from air pollution, BELA filed a writ petition for necessary direction to control vehicular air pollution in Dhaka City. In that case, the Supreme Court directed the government to, inter alia, phase out all existing two stroke three-wheeler vehicles, which were the most polluting vehicles, from Dhaka City by December, 2002. Although this was a difficult task, the government implemented the court direction. However, the implementation of this decision did not occasion the type of hardship and top- heavy court-mediated oversight discussed by Rajamani regarding the Delhi Vehicular pollution cases. “The government gave the three-wheeler owners many incentives and options and pushed them to the wall to accept these. For the most part, drivers were rehabilitated in some way or the other.” 142 However, this successful implementation outcome has not been replicated across the board. In many other cases, the decisions have not been properly implemented. Some of the projects that were successfully challenged by the activists were ultimately executed by the government. Some of these projects 140 Rajamani, “Public Interest Environmental Litigation in India: Exploring Issues of Access, Participation, Equity, Effectiveness and Sustainability”, supra note 126, at 309. 141 Dhaka City Vehicular Pollution Case, supra note 53 at 36. 142 “Air Pollution”, The Daily Star (24 April 2009). 32 Asian Journal of Comparative Law, Vol. 7 [2012], Iss. 1, Art. 13 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM have engendered serious environmental harm. For example, the FAP-20 project referred to above was ultimately improperly executed in defiance of the judgment. In the judgment on merit in the FAP 20 Case, A.K. Badrul Huq, J., observed that “in implementing the project the respondents cannot with impunity violate the provisions of law. We are of the view that the FAP-20 project work should be executed in compliance with the requirements of law.” 143 Unfortunately, government authorities have not followed the relevant principles of the applicable laws. They violated the directions of the court in the judgment. The worst part of the execution of the project is that no compensation has been paid to the people affected by it. As a result, BELA filed another writ petition against different government authorities to assess the compensation for the “Project Affected People”. 144 In this writ petition, the High Court Division issued a Rule Nisi, calling upon several government authorities. 145 However, any compensation for the said Project Affected People is yet to be realised. This goes to show that although the legal activists have been successful in achieving the recognition of the human right to a healthy environment, the real fruits of this jurisprudential development are not always easily translated into reality in the lives of the people. The vulnerabilities of judicial activism have been magnified with the recent deadlock in the relocation of the leather goods and processing industry in an effort to stop massive environmental pollution. The leather-processing industry is one of the oldest industries in Bangladesh. It is mainly located on the banks of the Buriganga, one of the main rivers at the heart of the capital city of this country. Bangladesh has more than 200 leather goods and processing companies, and at least 178 of these are located in 50 acres of land on the banks of the Buriganga. 146 They process hides into finished leather using acids and chromium, producing roughly 20 million square metres of leather and leather goods each year. They account for an average of 1.5 per cent of the total exports of this country over the last three years. 147 The most important feature of this industry is the fact that it is the main water polluter in this country. None of the companies within this industry has an effluent management plant, and most of their 30,000 workers work in chemical- filled environments without the required protective equipment. It is notoriously 143 FAP 20 Judgment on Merit, supra note 9. 144 Bangladesh Environmental Lawyers Association (BELA) v. Bangladesh and others, Writ Petition No. 1691 of 2001(hereinafter PAP Case). 145 BELA, “List of Public Interest Litigation”, online: (last accessed 30 January 2009). 146 Satadal Sarkar, “When Will the Waste Flow in the Buriganga Stop?” The Prothom Alo (Dhaka) (10 November 2010). 147 Product-Wise and Region-Wise exports, the Ministry of Commerce of the Government of Bangladesh, online: (last accessed 14 February 2011). 33 Karim et al.: LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE Published by De Gruyter, 2012 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM the most significant water polluter in Bangladesh: the leather industry alone pollutes 26 per cent of the total river water of Bangladesh. 148 People living near these tanneries are “exposed to higher morbidity and mortality compared to people living two to three kilometres away”. 149 A recent report shows that the leather goods and processing plants of different companies (particularly on the banks of the Buriganga) have dumped approximately 3,000 tons of liquid waste in the Buriganga. In effect, they have turned this river into a toxic dump by indiscriminately discharging their waste into it. 150 Given these circumstances, the government has decided to shift these manufacturing units to a 200-acre industrial zone near the capital city. Bangladesh Small and Cottage Industries Corporation (BSCIC) has developed this zone for these units at a cost of US$66.42 million, and has almost finalised the process for establishing a central effluent plant in this zone, at a cost of US$61.42 million. Nonetheless, this relocation is at a crossroads. In 2003, the High Court Division finally provided a guideline, which is mandatory for all residents of this country according to the constitution of Bangladesh, to facilitate the relocation. However, the industry owners and government authorities have failed to begin the move. 151 The court has repeatedly provided more time, but the relocation has not advanced. 152 This regulatory deadlock syndrome can be traced back to the notification of August 7, 1986, when the Ministry of Local Government, Rural Development and Cooperatives identified 903 industrial units of 14 sectors as polluters. It directed the Department of Environment, the Ministry of Environment and Forests and the Ministry of Industries to ensure appropriate pollution control measures were undertaken by these industries within three years. The notification also obliged these authorities to ensure that no new industry could be established without pollution-fighting devices. However, between 1986 and 1994, they failed to ensure that these industries undertook any suitable pollution control measures. In 1994, BELA filed a writ petition before the High Court Division of the Supreme Court of Bangladesh seeking relief against the indiscriminate pollution 148 Mohammad Golam Rasul, Faisal Islam & Mohammad Masud Kamal Khan, “Environmental Pollution Generated from Process industries in Bangladesh” (2006) 28(1) International Journal of Environment and Pollution 144. 149 A.K. Enamul Haque, “Human Health and Human Welfare Costs of Environmental Pollution from the Tanning Industry in Dhaka – An Environmental Impact Study” in Moinul islam Sharif & Khandaker Mainuddin, Country Case Study on Environmental Requirements for Leather and Footwear Export from Bangladesh (Dhaka: Bangladesh Centre for Advanced Studies, 2003) at 10. 150 Sharif & Mainuddin, ibid. at 9; for details and the source of this information, see Sarkar, “When Will the Waste Flow in the Buriganga Stop?”, supra note 146. 151 Anisur Rahman Khan, “Tanneries Relocation Move Hits Roadblock” The Independent (Dhaka) (21 July 2010). 152 Ibid.; Satadal Sarkar, “When Will the Waste Flow in the Buriganga Stop?”, supra note 146. 34 Asian Journal of Comparative Law, Vol. 7 [2012], Iss. 1, Art. 13 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM of air, water, soil and the environment by 903 industrial units. These units included tanneries; paper, pulp, and sugar mills; distilleries; as well as the iron and steel, fertiliser, insecticide and pesticide, chemical, cement, pharmaceutical, textile, rubber and plastic, tyre and tube and jute industries. 153 It was pled that, though the air and water of the major rivers of this country were being severely affected by these 903 units, the government organisations responsible had failed to tackle this damage to the ecological system. The petitioner, moreover, informed the court that the number of polluting units had risen to 1,176, according to the list prepared by the Department of Environment. In the first instance, the court issued a Rule Nisi to the respondents, including the Ministry of Local Government, Rural Development and Cooperatives, Ministry of Environment and Forest, Ministry of Industries and Department of Environment to show cause as to why they should not be directed to implement the decisions of the Government. After hearing all the parties, the Rule was made absolute. On July 15, 2001, the court directed the Director General of the Department of Environment to implement the decision to mitigate the pollution by the original 903 units within six months from the date of the judgment. The court directed to “report to this Court after six months by furnishing concerned affidavit showing that compliance of this Order of this Court.” 154 To ensure the implementation of the court’s directions, it was further held that “it will be imperative on the part of the Director General to take penal action against such department for persons who are responsible for not implementing the letter of the Environment Conservation Act, 1995.” 155 Of these 903 industrial units, most are leather goods and processing companies. Of the 178 tanneries situated on the bank of Buriganga, 158 have been red-listed by the Department of Environment. 156 None of these companies has any kind of effluent plant, which has virtually transformed the Buriganga into a pool of septic water. 157 According to the environmental laws of Bangladesh, this situation is intolerable. BELA brought this issue before the High Court Division of the Supreme Court of Bangladesh and claimed directions for relocating these units from the bank of the Buriganga. 158 The court issued a Rule Nisi on March 3, 153 Industrial Pollution Case, supra note 9. 154 Ibid. A synopsis of this case is available at Bangladesh Environmental Lawyers association, “List of Selected Public interest Litigation (PIL) of BELA”, online: (last accessed 22 October 2011). 155 Ibid. 156 A.K. Enamul Haque, “Human Health and Human Welfare Costs of Environmental Pollution from the Tanning Industry in Dhaka—An Environmental Impact Study”, supra note 149 at 9, 10. 157 Anisur Rahman Khan, “Tanneries Relocation Move Hits Roadblock” The Independent (Dhaka) (21 July 2010). 158 Bangladesh Environmental Lawyers Association (BELA) v. Bangladesh and Others, Writ Petition No. 1430 of 2003. 35 Karim et al.: LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE Published by De Gruyter, 2012 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM 2003, and called upon the seven government agencies and two tannery associations as respondents. The court summoned the Secretaries of the Ministries of Industries and Commerce and Environment and Forest; the Director General and the Director of the Department of Environment; a member of the Planning Commission; and the chairmen of RAJUK (the capital city development authority), BSCIC, and the Tanners Association. They were asked to show cause as to why they should not be directed to relocate the tanneries from the city to a suitable location, as contemplated in the Master Plan prepared under the Town Improvement Act 1953, within 18 months from the date of judgment. The court directed them to ensure that adequate pollution-fighting devices were developed in the new location or site as required under the Environment Conservation Act 1995 and the Factories Act 1965. They were also directed to notify the court regarding the process of the relocation of the tanneries and submit a report in this regard to the court within six months. This petition is still pending before the court. While failing to treat these tanneries according to the provisions mentioned in the Act and other related laws, the government is trying to relocate them to a well-planned leather industry zone near the city; an industrial zone has been developed with adequate industrial plots for them. Many of them have obtained their plots in the new industrial zone where the construction of an effluent plant is underway. Nonetheless, the tanneries are not interested in moving from the banks of the Buriganga. They maintain that they will not consider relocating until the government (a) pays them $155.57 million as compensation, (b) discharges them from the debt they owe to the commercial banks, (c) provides them loans at a low interest rate, and (d) ensures that the government will bear the cost of maintaining the effluent plant. In 2006, a committee, formed by the secretaries of the government ministries concerned, suggested the government pay $33.60 million to the tanneries as compensation. 159 Both parties are standing their ground with respect to their remaining demands. The PIL filed by BELA is still pending before the court. According to Article 112 of the Constitution of Bangladesh, all executive and judicial agencies are obliged to carry out the directions of the High Court Division of the Supreme Court of Bangladesh. Unfortunately, these respondents have not been able to carry out the court’s directions; they have sought more time from the court, and the court has allowed them time for the ends of justice. Meanwhile, the Buriganga has been becoming increasingly toxic, and the government is losing its investment in preparing a modern leather industrial zone. At this time, the respondents have extended their time to carry out the court’s directions, and nobody knows when they will reach a concrete solution. 159 Abul Hasnat & Suvongkor Kormokar, “Leather Industry Passing a Critical Situation” The Prothom Alo (5 November 2011). 36 Asian Journal of Comparative Law, Vol. 7 [2012], Iss. 1, Art. 13 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM Long-term indirect effects of court decisions are more difficult to measure. However, the recognition, publicity, and impetus that these decisions have given to the legal activists as intimated above are all part of the indirect effect; they amount to political capital that could supplement other movement strategies outside the courts. Beyond these, there are other signs of long-term effectiveness of decided cases, even in cases with adverse short-term outcomes. For example, in BELA v. Bangladesh (Modhumoti Model Town Case), 160 the petitioner challenged the legality of a land development project that interfered with natural drainage by making changes to the flood flow/sub-flood flow zones near Dhaka City contrary to the Dhaka Metropolitan Master Plan. However, the court ruled that although the project is illegal, the interest of the third party purchasers of plots of land in Modhumoti Model Town should be protected as they are bona fide purchasers for value without notice. 161 In the short run, this was not the complete positive outcome that BELA hoped for. However, in 2008, the government announced that it was going to amend rules to stop unplanned urbanisation across the country. The first rule for private housing projects that resulted from the Modhumoti Model Town Case only applied to the Rajdhani Unnayan Kartripakkha (Rajuk) areas. 162 2. Sustainability According to Rajamani, in India, the phenomenon of endless judicial oversight in public interest cases is not sustainable for several reasons. It takes up the time of the court and hampers the functioning of the judicial system. The courts are able to cope with the time constraints in part by appointing committees whose ad hoc nature may lead to inconsistencies and possible inequities. Furthermore, such lengthy court oversight leads to reactive instead of proactive administration. It also creates an unhealthy and tension-ridden relationship of dependence and places tremendous strain on government resources. 163 As noted above, in the context of the Delhi Pollution Case, Rosencranz and Jackson pointed out the likelihood of the strong stance of the Supreme Court leading to impediment of capacity building in the pollution control agencies and compromise of the development of sustained environmental management in India. 164 160 Bangladesh Environment Lawyers Association (BELA) v. Bangladesh, Represented by the Secretary, Ministry of Housing and Public Works and others, Writ Petition No. 4604 of 2004 (Judgment on 27 July 2005, unreported) (Modhumoti Model Town Case). 161 Ibid. 162 “Amended Rules Soon to Stop Unplanned Urbanisation” The Daily Star (21 July 2008). 163 Rajamani, “Public Interest Environmental Litigation in India: Exploring Issues of Access, Participation, Equity, Effectiveness and Sustainability”, supra note 126, at 315–316. 164 A. Rosencranz & M. Jackson, “The Delhi Pollution Case: The Supreme Court of India and the Limits of Judicial Power”, supra note 126. 37 Karim et al.: LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE Published by De Gruyter, 2012 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM The foregoing concerns are increasingly applicable to Bangladesh, where the Supreme Court has a tendency to follow its Indian counterpart in environmental cases. Lawyers in Bangladesh frequently refer to Indian judgments, and the judges also cite Indian cases in their judgments, as is evident in some of the cases discussed in this paper. Recently, like the Indian Supreme Court, Bangladeshi courts have started maintaining lengthy oversight of the implementation of their decisions. For example, in BELA v. Bangladesh (MT Enterprise Case), the Supreme Court issued the following order: The Government is directed to set up a High Level Technical Committee comprising representatives from Ministry/Department of Shipping, the Ministry/Department of Environment, Ministry of Labour and Manpower; Retired Naval officers; Academicians/Experts in the field of Marine Engineering and Marine Biology; Specialist in the field of Environment, Science and Ecology, [and] Hazardous Waste Management; and relevant NGOs, such as BELA. 165 Similarly, in Rabia Bhuiyan, MP v. Ministry of LGRD and others, the Appellate Division of the Supreme Court maintained lengthy oversight of its decision requiring, inter alia, a yearly report on steps taken to implement the relevant policy. 166 In adopting this measure, the court relied on two decisions of the Supreme Court of India. These were MC Mehta v. Union of India 167 (the Delhi Pollution Case), where the court required the submission of regular reports by a committee it set up, and the ruling of the High Court Division in the Dhaka City Vehicular Pollution Case, 168 where the court deemed the case pending for the purpose of monitoring and required six-monthly reports. In short, few will doubt that litigation does not yield long-term social change. Notwithstanding, some social movement theories indicate that there is a danger of the continued employment of litigation even after it has outlived its usefulness as a strategy or when other strategies would be more effective. The transformation of social movement organisation may take place in several ways, including by “organisational maintenance”. In this phenomenon, “the primary activity of the organization becomes the maintenance of membership, funds, and other requirements of organizational existence.” 169 The danger of this sort of 165 Bangladesh Environmental Lawyers Association (BELA) v. Bangladesh, Represented by the Secretary, Ministry of Shipping and others (Unreported, order dated 05 March 2009 and 17 March 2009), online: (last accessed 9 May 2009) at [9]. 166 Rabia Bhuiyan, MP v. Ministry of LGRD and others, 55 DLR (AD) 184 (2007) at [29]. 167 6 SCC 12 1999 at [2.4]. 168 Dhaka City Vehicular Pollution Case, supra note 53 at [15]. 169 M. Zald & R. Ash, “Social Movement Organizations: Growth, Decay and Change” in J. Goodwin and J. Jasper, eds., Social Movements, supra note 117 at 76. 38 Asian Journal of Comparative Law, Vol. 7 [2012], Iss. 1, Art. 13 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM transformation is all too real when an organisation such as BELA becomes defined by success in high profile cases with the attendant recognition and publicity. In such cases, the temptation to maintain the status quo is high. The word of caution here is that organisational maintenance should not be allowed to supplant the original environmental pursuits. 3. Access and Participation Rajamani also argued that there is a tremendous scope for value preferences in PILs because of the characteristic procedural flexibility, collaborative approach, judicially supervised interim orders, and the forward-looking reliefs. The courts are thus perceived as middle class intellectuals that are more receptive to others of their ilk. This perception, argues Rajamani, is in itself deeply restrictive for participation. Furthermore, litigation cost factors contrive to alienate the poor from the portals of the courts, such that PILs are filed on behalf of the poor and not by them. 170 Room for biases and value preferences characteristic of whatever echelon of the society the judges belong to would seem to be inevitable, with the procedural flexibility that continues to be a feature of PILs in India. There are also signs that Bangladeshi courts are not immune to this charge. In reading some of the judgements cited in this paper, one could not but notice some instances in which the judges seem not to be particularly fettered by extant limitations of the law. For example, in the decision of the Appellate Division to maintain administrative oversight of its ruling in Rabia Bhuiyan, MP v. Ministry of LGRD and others, there was no analysis by the court to provide some basis in law for such a novel role for the courts. The court chose instead to place reliance on the fact that the Indian Supreme Court had done the same thing. In the same vein, the courts are likely to be flexible in other aspects of their exercise of PIL jurisdiction, such that the scope for discretion is enlarged. The degree to which the blame for this shortcoming should be apportioned between the judges, who reach the decisions, and the legal activists, who frame the claims, is difficult to determine without further research. However, both can play a role in attenuating this feature of PIL in Bangladesh. The judges can self- restrain, while the activists should, in framing their claims, bear in mind that there is much to be gained from the continued objectivity of the judiciary. Perhaps the activists in Bangladesh have an opportunity to play a role here because there are fewer organisations engaged in PIL and some of the organisations have initiated educational programs that include environmental training for judges. Having said this, in seeking to reform this area of law, regard 170 Ibid. at 302–303. 39 Karim et al.: LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE Published by De Gruyter, 2012 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM must also be paid to some of the plausible raison d'être of the flexibility that attaches to PIL, as adumbrated in some of the extenuation commentaries above. Care must also be taken to not overemphasise this limitation, because different forms of biases and value preferences are equally true of the judiciary in most countries on various issues, whether or not the environment is in issue, and whether or not the courts countenance PILs. Furthermore, for Bangladesh, anybody familiar with the state of the poor would agree that there are real obstacles to the poor representing themselves. The poor have neither the financial resources nor the technical knowhow for self- representation. Indeed, understanding the issues at stake in some environmental matters would usually be an uphill task for the general populace. One can only imagine the difficulty that would be involved in explaining the health issues in the Radiated Milk Case to the underprivileged. Most of the poor would ordinarily view the tainted product as affordable milk. The same is true regarding the ship breaking and shrimp cultivation cases; many would understandably see the impugned activities as sources of income and nothing more because the dangers and adverse effects are not immediately apparent. These limitations leave representative litigation as one of the few viable options. Having said this, it is equally true that it is a failure of Bangladeshi environmental legal activism that poor people seem to have a minimal role in the decision-making process. A recent incident buttresses this point. On February 22, 2010, newspaper reports indicated that workers of shipbreaking yards “staged a protest against a new national import policy that requires all vessels destined for recycling in Chittagong to carry a pre-cleaning certificate.” 171 This policy is a direct result of the MT Enterprise Case referred to above. 172 However, there is an allegation that this kind of protests is fake and mostly carried out by people hired by the shipbreaking industry owners. 173 Notwithstanding, whereas this protest demonstrates that segments of the society were unhappy with the decision, it would be naive to conclude that this is the sole or predominant view on the matter, because there are other views. In a video clip on a webpage in the website of the Goldman Prize, the Chief Executive of BELA contends that ship breaking is a trade of hazardous waste in disguise, since the ships are not pre-cleaned before being sent to Bangladesh and as such release toxic wastes into the coastal area. She informed that they received reports 171 Liz McCarthy, “Bangladesh Shipbreaking Protest Slammed as Fake” Lloyed's List, online: (last accessed 17 December 2010). 172 Bangladesh Environmental Lawyers Association (BELA) v. Bangladesh, Represented by the Secretary, Ministry of Shipping and others, supra note 165. 173 McCarthy, supra note 171. 40 Asian Journal of Comparative Law, Vol. 7 [2012], Iss. 1, Art. 13 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM of deaths in the shipbreaking yards at least once a month. 174 She also notes, “[this] is polluting the coastal environment, affecting the fishermen, killing so many labourers so on that ground we move against this very hazardous operation of the industry.” 175 The clip also featured a young woman who had lost her husband in a ship-breaking yard accident, and another man who claims to have been disabled due to an accident sustained in one of the yards. BELA selects the cases it files from hundreds that are reported to it with requests for redress. 176 Hence, although the underprivileged would in some instances be adversely affected by some of the decisions, it is still a segment of that same constituency that seems to animate BELA’s litigation activities, and the same may be said for at least some of the cases filed by the other legal activist organisations. Using the shipbreaking cases as an example, the question then is how to balance the right to life of the workers and the health of the people in the coastal area against the right of all the workers in the ship breaking and ancillary industries to a means of livelihood. Perhaps a balance could be struck if litigation is used sparingly as a last resort, and even then with extensive consultation with the stakeholders and assessment of the impact of the anticipated reliefs on the less privileged. Imaginative reliefs could then be sought with emphasis on how to reduce the negative impact of possible rulings on those dependent on the impugned industry or activity. Perhaps the courts could also encourage out-of- court settlements with a view to encouraging the leaders in each industry to contribute to phased implementation and the rehabilitation of those who would be affected. The possibility of an adverse ruling should encourage all to negotiate a settlement outside the courts. The main justification of PIL in Bangladesh is, for the most part, that the poor and underprivileged are unable to represent themselves. With appropriate 174 The Goldman Environmental Prize, “Syeda Rizwana Hasan”, online: (last accessed 28 June 2009). 175 Ibid. 176 There are no official statistics regarding human casualties in these yards. The figures relating to these casualties are dependent on regular local media releases complied by local NGOs. According to these sources, 500 people died over the last fifteen years, with 200 deaths occurring in the last five years. In both cases, these deaths amount to between 1,000–1,200 over the last three decades, assuming that the annual loss of life of shipbreaking workers is more or less the same in each year. However, these figures do not cover the deaths of workers who die as a result of chronic diseases due to exposure to toxic substances. For details, Erdem Vardar et al., “End of Life Ships: The Human Cost of Breaking Ships” (December 2005). This report can be found online at (last accessed 14 November 2011). For a detailed discussion on the PIL related with labour regulation of this industry, see Md. Saiful Karim, “Violation of Labour Rights in the Ship-Breaking Yards of Bangladesh: Legal Norms and Reality” (2009) 25(4) Int’l J. Comp. Lab. L. & Ind. Rel. 379. 41 Karim et al.: LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE Published by De Gruyter, 2012 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM environmental enlightenment, even where the poor are unable to access the courts, other forms of action, such as protest, would be viable. 177 In sum, PILs do have limitations. Environmental PILs have had mixed results in Bangladesh in practical terms. The picture of a handful of activists continuing indefinitely to represent the poor and defend the environmental causes is not a pretty one. 178 The attendant lengthy judicial oversight of PIL-engendered decisions is certainly unsustainable. Perhaps these facts are not lost on the activists. The chief executive of BELA, for example, is reported to have reflected that “some of the most significant achievements in environmental law and policy reform have resulted from the patient dialogue and relationship building that she and her colleagues at BELA have advocated.” 179 Given credit to the civil society groups and the courts for developing an awareness and legal activism in environmental regulation in Bangladesh, a core question is whether the judiciary could be an engine of social change. Rosenberg doubts the feasibility of such a role. He has developed court types – a dynamic court model and a constrained court model – and tests the impact of these courts by examining social policies and practices before and after a number of apex courts’ decisions often regarded as important sources of social change. He finds that the courts decisions have had no or virtually no significant independent direct or indirect effect on social change. He argued that special change depends on other factors like political efforts wholly separate from the court system. 180 Rajamani also assessed the impact of the leading PILs on the social changes in India. He finds that the legal activism has been able to provide some “chemotherapy for the carcinogenic body politic” 181 and exemplary work. 177 Marc Galanter has explained the theoretical issues related with such dilemma. For details see M. Galanter, “Why the ‘haves’ come out ahead: Speculations on the limits of legal change” (1974) 9 Law & Soc’y Rev. 95-160; See also Shahnaz Huda, Protecting the Common Good: Successes in Public Interest Litigation (Dhaka: Asia Foundation, 2002). 178 For instance, in the last few years, Human Rights and Peace for Bangladesh, an NGO, alone has filed more than 50 PILs. In these PILs, this NGO along with its president Advocate Mr. Monjil Murshed, has sought judicial direction for multifarious issues ranging from the issues related with the evacuation of markets from car parks, police action for protecting minorities, publication of investigation report of a murder case, illegal encroachment of rivers and so on. We tried to get details of this NGO’s PIL profile, but did not get in its website. The website does not even provide details of its contact. The link of its website is . 179 McQuay & Kabir, “Reflecting on Rizwana Hasan’s Goldman environmental Prize”, supra note 114. 180 G. Rosenberg, The Hollow Hope: Can Courts Bring About Social Change? (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1991) at xii+425; G. Rosenberg, “Hollow Hopes and Other Aspirations: A Reply to Feeley and McCann” (1993) 17 Law & Soc. Inquiry 761-778; for a critique of Rosenberg’s arguments, see M. Feeley, “Hollow Hopes, Flypaper, and Metaphors” 17 Law & Social Inquiry 745-760. 181 U. Baxi, “Preface” in S.P. Sathe, ed., Judicial Activism in India (New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2002). 42 Asian Journal of Comparative Law, Vol. 7 [2012], Iss. 1, Art. 13 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM However, he raises concerns over the exercise of public interest environmental jurisdiction with respect to access, participation, effectiveness, and sustainability. 182 The discussion above also shows that legal activism in Bangladesh often developed “policy evolution fora” for a particular national issue and gets into the executive governance with judicial governance in sectors highlighted by a group of public interest litigants. 183 Along with an insufficient impact on a substantive change into the social movement, this type of overlapping in the major organs of the State reveal some dissatisfaction with the judicial process. The social change motion set by the judicial activism in this country, in most cases, is less than participatory; therefore, arguably, this has led to unrealistic solutions. Some stakeholders have already raised their voices against this activism, claiming that the solutions provided from the court system are, in most cases, ineffective and unsustainable. In PIL, the court can focus more on the development of some principles to solve a particular issue, and it should not get heavily involved in regulating the organisations of the government. It should, rather, boost the notion of “new governance”, where the governance is less reliant on state-dictated preferences and more on public-private collaboration, flexibility, and pragmatism. 184 Legal activism can push the political system to take the agents related to social change onto the board. To put this pressure on the political system and to bring other agents of social change into the governance system, courts can use PIL as a forum. V. CONCLUDING REMARKS The aim of PIL is to provide the opportunity for any member of the society to use the judicial activism to obtain redress for any activities detrimental to public welfare. It is a means by which the apex court can deal with public rights and liabilities within the constitutional framework and can direct the government agencies to address any issue ruled to be against the public interest. In a society where poverty and corruption are prevalent and corporate society has a strong 182 L. Rajamani, “Public Interest Environmental Litigation in India: Exploring Issues of Access, Participation, Equity, Effectiveness and Sustainability”,supra note 126 at 296. 183 It would be worth mentioning the latest reported PIL at this point. In a leave to appeal against High Court Division order in Writ Petition No. 3503 on 2009, the Appellate Division of the Supreme Court of Bangladesh has put the maxim “Salus Papuli Suprema lex” in the imperative, that is, “Salus Papuli suprema lex esto” – let the safety of the people be the supreme law. The impact of this notion taken by the apex court would be many. One of those effects would be the use of PIL as a means of getting personal redress. For details, see 62 DLR(AD) 2010, at 428–435. 184 Bradley Karkkainen, “New Governance In Legal Thought And In The World: Some Splitting As Antidote To Overzealous Lumping” (2004) 89 Minn. L. Rev. 471. 43 Karim et al.: LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE Published by De Gruyter, 2012 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM influence on political society, PIL could be an effective way through which the judicial activism can insist that public and private organisations are more accountable, especially against the backdrop of the legislatures’ apathy and the lack of political will in the executive branches. 185 However, its potential to create a strong peoples’ movement to reach their goal using PIL is not sufficient. Nevertheless, using PIL as a means, the outlook of legal activism creating a much more constructive role of society in general and informed groups in particular is rosy. It is likely that the organisations currently engaged in litigation would continue to file cases. However, the danger is that this is likely to continue even when short term remedial reliefs would be the only benefit as returns on long term movement-building benefits begin to diminish. The legal activists may find themselves increasingly engaged in organisational maintenance. Litigation, being reactive, would then be incapable of contributing to the desirable goal of sustainable environmental justice. Since litigation is already yielding movement- building benefits, this paper recommends that these be relied upon incrementally in the deployment of more sustainable strategies, such as education, lobbying, and other forms of participation in policy development. This calls for greater focus on strategies other than those presently adopted. However, this may necessitate the formation of new organisations with greater expertise in the new forms of political strategy. To be successful, the new entrants would have to form strong partnerships with the legal activists that have already gained reputation, prestige, and other forms of political capital. Therefore, the long-term success of the environmental social movement in Bangladesh may depend on the readiness of the established organisations to encourage and support new organisations with new strategies. The focus of this paper on the activities of social movement organisations should however not belie the fact that the implementation of environmental laws and policies remains, primarily, the responsibility of States. 185 P. Hassan & A. Azfar, “Securing Environmental Rights Through Public Interest Litigation In South Asia” (2003) 22 Va. Envtl. L.J. 215 at 246; For more details see R. Barnett, “The Civil Liberties Movement In India: New Approaches To The State And Social Change” (1987) 27(3) Asian Survey 371–392; A.K. Thiruvengadam, “In Pursuit of ‘The Common Illumination of Our House’: Trans-Judicial Influence and the Origins of PIL Jurisprudence In South Asia” (2008) 2 Indian Journal Of Constitution Law 67–103. 44 Asian Journal of Comparative Law, Vol. 7 [2012], Iss. 1, Art. 13 Brought to you by | Queensland University of Technology Authenticated | 131.181.251.20 Download Date | 7/26/13 4:10 AM Asian Journal of Comparative Law LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE LEGAL ACTIVISM FOR ENSURING ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE Abstract work_aswfatcz3ferlfxbu6726mcjfa ---- [PDF] Quantitative Literacy for Social Justice | Semantic Scholar Skip to search formSkip to main content> Semantic Scholar's Logo Search Sign InCreate Free Account You are currently offline. Some features of the site may not work correctly. DOI:10.1080/10665680601079894 Corpus ID: 42980338Quantitative Literacy for Social Justice @article{Wiest2007QuantitativeLF, title={Quantitative Literacy for Social Justice}, author={Lynda R. Wiest and H. Higgins and J. Frost}, journal={Equity & Excellence in Education}, year={2007}, volume={40}, pages={47 - 55} } Lynda R. Wiest, H. Higgins, J. Frost Published 2007 Sociology Equity & Excellence in Education In this article, we argue that many adults lack the “numeracy” needed to function in a maximally effective manner in their vocational, civic, and personal lives. We believe schools need to foster skills in quantitative literacy (QL), an inclination and ability to make reasoned decisions using general world knowledge and fundamental mathematics in authentic everyday circumstances. We explain how schools might begin to make inroads in preparing more quantitatively literate students and how this… Expand View on Taylor & Francis commons.hostos.cuny.edu Save to Library Create Alert Cite Launch Research Feed Share This Paper 29 CitationsHighly Influential Citations 2 Background Citations 10 View All 29 Citations Citation Type Citation Type All Types Cites Results Cites Methods Cites Background Has PDF Publication Type Author More Filters More Filters Filters Sort by Relevance Sort by Most Influenced Papers Sort by Citation Count Sort by Recency Rethinking the Numerate Citizen: Quantitative Literacy and Public Issues – Reply A. Erickson Sociology 2016 8 PDF Save Alert Research Feed Crossing the great divide: Teacher candidates, mathematics, and social justice Barbara Garii, Aina K. Appova Sociology 2013 13 Save Alert Research Feed The Contribution of Course Materials to a Social Justice Agenda: Lessons from a Quantitative Literacy Course for Undergraduate Social Science Students Duncan Mhakure, J. Jaftha, Sheena Rughubar-Reddy Sociology 2014 1 PDF Save Alert Research Feed Teaching Practical Numeracy Through Social Justice Pedagogy: Case Study of Abu Dhabi Women's College M. Tanko Engineering 2012 7 Save Alert Research Feed Pre-service teachers’ awareness of interdisciplinary connections: Mathematics, financial literacy, and social justice issues M. Tanase, Thomas A. Lucey Mathematics, Political Science 2017 2 View 2 excerpts, cites background Save Alert Research Feed There is Nothing “BASIC” about Numeracy in Higher Education - A Case Study from an Accounting Programme S. Rathilal Computer Science 2015 View 2 excerpts, cites background Save Alert Research Feed How participatory action research as pedagogy helped transform the identities of students enrolled in a developmental mathematics classroom G. Moreno, David Rutledge 2020 Save Alert Research Feed Preparing Preservice Elementary Teachers to Teach About Financial Literacy: Towards a Broader Conception Thomas A. Lucey Political Science 2016 7 Save Alert Research Feed Keeping It Real: Information Literacy, Numeracy, and Economic Data Diego Méndez-Carbajo, C. Jefferson, Katrina Stierholz, California State University-Northridge Computer Science 2019 3 PDF Save Alert Research Feed Assessing Numeracy in the Upper Elementary and Middle School Years Carol Ann Gittens Psychology 2015 1 Highly Influenced PDF View 4 excerpts, cites background Save Alert Research Feed ... 1 2 3 ... References SHOWING 1-10 OF 45 REFERENCES SORT BYRelevance Most Influenced Papers Recency Numeracy: The New Literacy for a Data-Drenched Society. L. Steen Psychology 1999 140 PDF View 3 excerpts, references background Save Alert Research Feed Reading And Writing The World With Mathematics: Toward a Pedagogy for Social Justice E. Gutstein Mathematics, Political Science 2005 460 Save Alert Research Feed Why Numbers Count: Quantitative Literacy For Tomorrow's America L. Steen Psychology 1998 172 View 2 excerpts, references background Save Alert Research Feed Making Mathematics Work for All Children: Issues of Standards, Testing, and Equity A. Schoenfeld Sociology 2002 396 View 1 excerpt, references background Save Alert Research Feed Quantitative Literacy for the Next Generation Z. Usiskin Political Science 2001 14 PDF View 1 excerpt, references background Save Alert Research Feed When Do Girls Prefer Football to Fashion? An analysis of female underachievement in relation to ‘realistic’ mathematic contexts J. Boaler Psychology 1994 128 Save Alert Research Feed Radical Equations : Math Literacy and Civil Rights N. Koblitz 2002 377 PDF Save Alert Research Feed The Democratization of Mathematics A. Carnevale, Donna M. Desrochers 2004 16 Highly Influential View 4 excerpts, references background Save Alert Research Feed Critical Social Numeracy D. Lake Sociology 2002 6 View 1 excerpt, references background Save Alert Research Feed 미국 NCTM의 Principles and Standards for School Mathematics에 나타난 수학과 교수,학습의 이론 최영한, 김미월 Psychology 2002 2,665 Save Alert Research Feed ... 1 2 3 4 5 ... Related Papers Abstract 29 Citations 45 References Related Papers Stay Connected With Semantic Scholar Sign Up About Semantic Scholar Semantic Scholar is a free, AI-powered research tool for scientific literature, based at the Allen Institute for AI. Learn More → Resources DatasetsSupp.aiAPIOpen Corpus Organization About UsResearchPublishing PartnersData Partners   FAQContact Proudly built by AI2 with the help of our Collaborators Terms of Service•Privacy Policy The Allen Institute for AI By clicking accept or continuing to use the site, you agree to the terms outlined in our Privacy Policy, Terms of Service, and Dataset License ACCEPT & CONTINUE work_ay4po53ouzeitbdpvracubt6em ---- Giddens | What is Graphic Justice? | The Comics Grid: Journal of Comics Scholarship Home News Search Articlesarrow_drop_down Submissionsarrow_drop_down Aboutarrow_drop_down Login Register Home News Search Articlesarrow_drop_down Submissionsarrow_drop_down Aboutarrow_drop_down Login Register menu Articles Collections Volumes Submissions Author Guidelines Start Submission About Become a Reviewer Research Integrity Editorial Team Articles Collections Volumes Submissions Author Guidelines Start Submission About Become a Reviewer Research Integrity Editorial Team Note What is Graphic Justice? Note What is Graphic Justice? Abstract This article reproduces a poster presented at the Socio-Legal Studies ­Association annual conference, 5–7 April 2016 at Lancaster University, UK. The poster outlines the emerging study of the legal and jurisprudential dimensions of comics. Seeking to answer the question ‘what is graphic justice?’, the poster highlights the variety of potential topics, questions, concerns, issues, and intersections that the crossover between law and comics might encounter. A transcript of the poster’s text is provided for easier reuse, as well as a list of references and suggested readings. Keywords graphic justice, justice, legal studies, law, poster How to Cite Giddens T., (2016) “What is Graphic Justice?”, The Comics Grid: Journal of Comics Scholarship 6(0). p.14. doi: https://doi.org/10.16995/cg.98 861 Views 76 Downloads The poster reproduced here (Figure 1) was presented at the Socio-Legal Studies Association annual conference, 5–7 April 2016 at Lancaster University1. This poster outlines the emerging study of the legal and jurisprudential dimensions of comics. Figure 1 “What is Graphic Justice?”. Seeking to answer the question ‘what is graphic justice?’, the poster highlights the variety of potential topics, questions, concerns, issues, and intersections that the crossover between law and comics might encounter. The poster also seeks to employ the comics form in its articulation of the vast potential of this under-explored area of legal and comics study. Methodology The poster was created primarily through manual illustration, with images scanned into GIMP 2 where they were digitally coloured, formatted and arranged, with digital text and graphics added. The reproduction here has been slightly amended (inclusion of author and Alliance details) from that originally presented at the conference. As the poster is an image file, a transcript of the poster’s text is provided below to enhance discoverability and reuse. Transcript Comic books, graphic novels, bandes dessinée, manga—whatever the chosen term, the comics medium remains under-researched in the legal academy. Aimed at rectifying this, the Graphic Justice Research Alliance is a multi-disciplinary research network exploring the crossover between law and justice and comics of all kinds. The intersection is an expansive and open one, and this poster indicates some key areas of critical insight and investigation in an attempt to begin to develop an answer to the question, ‘what is graphic justice?’ For more information on the Graphic Justice Research Alliance: Visit graphicjustice.blogspot.com | Follow @LexComica Representation of Law: Examples of law can be seen often in comics, and the visual depiction of judgment here indicates the sensory dimensions of law and justice. It is provocative in its suggestion of the towering (and divine?) power of law over the lives of its subjects. Object of Regulation: Comics arguably have a distinct multi-modality, with their unique blending of text, image, sequentiality, and graphic layout. Often with multiple creators, and with a history steeped in freedom of speech controversies due to their assumed ‘juvenility’, comics are complex objects of regulation traversing multiple areas of law. Legal Aesthetics: Law is always more than its texts. The visual image is here embedded within the text itself. Just like the multi-modal nature of comics in general, this example is symbolic of the aesthetic and visual dimensions of law and justice that comics can help us critically navigate. Sequentiality: A key dimension of comics form, the sequential images here invoke the narrative dimensions of law and legal processes. The emotive presentation of the subject under judgment further highlights the human aspects of legality—an important example of one of the many critical resources that comics bring to law. Visuality of Text: The written word is always visual in its appearance. Comics often manipulate the presentation of text in their articulation of meaning. Here we have provocatively strong, solid lettering—clear and powerful, indicative of law’s ideal of the presumed ‘plain texts’ that enable justice. Foundations of Justice: The arrangement of the text here might indicate that research is the foundation of justice; law should be informed, not instinctive. As a research alliance, this implies community and society may also be part of what grounds justice. Notes Socio-Legal Studies Association Annual Conference 2016, http://www.lancaster.ac.uk/law/slsa2016/ (Accessed 30 November 2016). [^] Competing Interests An outline proposal for this poster was peer reviewed before its acceptance for presentation at the SLSA 2016. The author is a section editor of The Comics Grid: Journal of Comics Scholarship and leads the Graphic Justice Research Alliance. This note was handled by another editor and underwent a standard triple-copyediting process. References J Bainbridge, (2007).  ‘This Is the Authority. This Planet Is under Our Protection’: An Exegesis of Superheroes’ Interrogations of Law.  Law, Culture and the Humanities 3 (3) : 455. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/1743872107081431 N Curtis, (2016).  Sovereignty and Superheroes. Manchester: Manchester University Press, DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.7228/manchester/9780719085048.001.0001 T Giddens, (2012).  Comics, Law, and Aesthetics: Towards the Use of Graphic Fiction in Legal Studies.  Law and Humanities 6 (1) : 85. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.5235/175214812800745672 T Giddens, (2015).  Graphic Justice: Intersections of Comics and Law. London: Routledge. P Goodrich, (1995).  Oedipus Lex: Psychoanalysis, History, Law. Berkeley: California University Press. T Groensteen, (2007).  The System of Comics. Jackson: University Press of Mississippi, DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.14325/mississippi/9781617038044.001.0001 WP MacNeil, (2007).  Lex Populi: The Jurisprudence of Popular Culture. Stanford: Stanford University Press. H Miodrag, (2013).  Comics and Language: Reimagining Critical Discourse on the Form. Jackson: University Press of Mississippi. WJT Mitchell, (1986).  Iconology: Image, Text, Ideology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. A Nyberg, (1998).  Seal of Approval: The History of the Comics Code. Jackson: University Press of Mississippi. N D Phillips, S Strobl, (2013).  Comic Book Crime: Truth, Justice, and the American Way. New York: New York University Press. L G Romero, I Dahlman, (2012).  Justice Framed: Law in Comics and Graphic Novels.  Law Text Culture 16 (special issue, open access). Available at: http://ro.uow.edu.au/ltc/vol16/iss1/. Share Authors Thomas Giddens (St Mary's University, Twickenham) Download Download XML Download PDF Issues Volume 6 • 2016 Graphic Justice Dates Submitted 2016-11-01 Published 2016-12-15 Licence Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Peer Review This article has been peer reviewed. File Checksums (MD5) XML: bf13adb3df6fb36a9757e93f53669489 PDF: 54573afa11416a82471d7b5bd9179822 Table of Contents Non Specialist Summary This article has no summary Close | 2048-0792 | Published by Open Library of Humanities | Privacy Policy | work_ay64kbu3yjhypasjk4qowlvlfe ---- Knight, C., and Albertsen, A. (2015) Rawlsian justice and palliative care. Bioethics, 29(8), pp. 536-542. (doi:10.1111/bioe.12156) This is the author’s final accepted version. There may be differences between this version and the published version. You are advised to consult the publisher’s version if you wish to cite from it. http://eprints.gla.ac.uk/103791/ Deposited on: 8 June 2015 Enlighten – Research publications by members of the University of Glasgow http://eprints.gla.ac.uk http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/bioe.12156 http://eprints.gla.ac.uk/103791/ http://eprints.gla.ac.uk/103791/ http://eprints.gla.ac.uk/ http://eprints.gla.ac.uk/ 1 RAWLSIAN JUSTICE AND PALLIATIVE CARE* Carl Knight1 and Andreas Albertsen2 ABSTRACT Palliative care serves both as an integrated part of treatment and as a last effort to care for those we cannot cure. The extent to which palliative care should be provided and our reasons for doing so have been curiously overlooked in the debate about distributive justice in health and health care. We argue that one prominent approach, the Rawlsian approach developed by Norman Daniels, is unable to provide such reasons and such care. This is because of a central feature in Daniels’ account, namely that care should be provided to restore people’s opportunities. Daniels view is both unable to provide pain relief to those who need it as a supplement to treatment and without justice-based reasons to provide palliative care to those whose opportunities cannot be restored. We conclude that this makes Daniels’ framework much less attractive. I. INTRODUCTION Arguably the most prominent theory of distributive justice is that developed by John Rawls. His concern is with the distribution of primary goods, understood as ‘things which it is supposed a man wants whatever else he wants’.3 Rawls is specifically focused on ‘the chief primary goods at the disposition of society’, which are ‘rights, liberties, and * This article is, as of early 2015, in press with Bioethics. The ‘Early View’ online version is available at http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12156/abstract. Funding: British Academy (grant number pf100118). 1 Department of Politics, University of Glasgow, Glasgow, UK; Department of Politics, University of Johannesburg, Auckland Park, South Africa. 2 Department of Political Science and Government, Aarhus University, School of Business and Social Sciences, Aarhus, Denmark 3 John Rawls. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press, 1971): 92. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/bioe.12156/abstract 2 opportunities, and income and wealth’ and ‘the social bases of self-respect’.4 The focus on social primary goods prompted critiques pointing out that this is unfair towards people who are disadvantaged in their natural characteristics.5 This critique is especially relevant in the area of health and healthcare, which Rawls says little about.6 In his introduction to Political Liberalism he suggest that ‘[b]asic health care assured all citizens’ is an ‘institution required for … stability’.7 But given that political stability is consistent with low levels of health care coverage, this is hardly an adequate reason to supply it. Elsewhere Rawls leaves decisions over the provision of healthcare to the legislative stage.8 Though acknowledging such shortfalls in Rawls’ work, Norman Daniels maintained that ‘[p]roperly extended, Rawls’ theory captures just the structure of our responses [to inequalities in capabilities sets] in a plausible way’.9 This article sets out to consider this extension in the context of the pain relieving practices known as palliative care. This is an increasingly important aspect of contemporary health care.10 4 Ibid: 62, 178. 5 K. J. Arrow. Some Ordinalist-Utilitarian Notes on Rawls’s Theory of Justice by John Rawls. The Journal of Philosophy 1973; 70: 254; W. Kymlicka. 1990. Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press: 71–73; A. Sen. 1987. Equality of What?. In Liberty, Equality, and Law: Selected Tanner Lectures on Human Values, S. McMurrin, ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 157–62. This move may also be due in part to Rawls’ failure to resolve the problem of commensurating social primary goods in an index: K. J. Arrow. Op. Cit.; R. J. Arneson. Primary Goods Reconsidered. 1990. Noûs 24, no. 3: 429–54; J. Roemer. 1996. Theories of Distributive Justice. Cambridge Mass: Harvard University Press: chap. 5. We are not concerned with this problem here. 6 Rawls often assumes away this discussion, asserting ‘that while citizens do not have equal capacities, they do have, at least to the essential minimum degree, the moral, intellectual and physical capacities that enable them to be fully co-operating members of society’ John Rawls. 1999. Collected Papers. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press: 183. See also: Ibid: 259; John Rawls. 2011. Justice as Fairness: A Restatement. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press: 58, 60, 170. 7 John Rawls. 1996. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press: lviii–lix. 8 Ibid: 184; Rawls, Justice as Fairness: 173–176. 9 Norman Daniels. Equality of What: Welfare, Resources, or Capabilities?. 1990. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research; 50: 283. 10 R. Sean Morrison et al., The Growth of Palliative Care Programs in United States Hospitals. Journal of Palliative Medicine 2005; 8: 1127–34; Udo SchüKlenk et al., End-of-Life Decision-Making in Canada: The Report by the Royal Society of Canada Expert Panel on End-of-Life Decision-Making: End-of-Life Decision-Making in Canada. Bioethics 2011; 25: 1–73; Jan Stjernswärd, Sophie M. Colleau, and Vittorio Ventafridda. The World 3 WHO defines palliative care as: ‘an approach that improves the quality of life of patients and their families facing the problem associated with life-threatening illness, through the prevention and relief of suffering’.11 The importance of palliative care is acknowledged in a wide variety of situations.12 But despite growing importance for medical practice, little theoretical work has been done to integrate the idea into work on distributive justice in health and healthcare. Addressing this very issue, the article brings an important practical aspect into the discussion of the most prominent theory of distributive justice in medical ethics. It does so by first presenting Daniels’ now famous account of Rawlsian justice in health and healthcare. Afterwards it raises two criticism of this position in relation to palliative care. One is that Daniels’ account is indifferent toward the pain associated with treatment and unable to prefer the less painful of two equally effective treatments. The other is that when little or nothing can be done in terms of treatment, Daniels view doesn´t give us good reason to relieve people’s pain. In both discussions several proposals for maintaining Daniels view are discussed, including a recent argument for the viability of Daniels’ account in relation to palliative care.13 We also consider responses suggested by the wider Rawlsian literature. Finding none of these persuasive, we conclude that on account of its inability to provide convincing answers in relation to this important topic, the Rawlsian enterprise loses much of its appeal in a health context. Health Organization Cancer Pain and Palliative Care Program Past, Present, and Future. Journal of Pain and Symptom Management 1996; 12: 65–72. 11 WHO, “Definition of Palliative” (WHO Geneva, 2009), http://www.who.int/cancer/palliative/definition/en. 12 C. Blinderman. Palliative Care, Public Health and Justice: Setting Priorities in Resource Poor Countries. Developing World Bioethics 2009; 9: 106; K. W. Carroll et al., Influences on Decision Making Identified by Parents of Children Receiving Pediatric Palliative Care. AJOB Primary Research 2012; 3: 1–7; S. J. Goodlin et al., Consensus Statement: Palliative and Supportive Care in Advanced Heart Failure. Journal of Cardiac Failure 2004; 10: 200–209; C. Sepúlveda et al., Palliative Care. Journal of Pain and Symptom Management 2002; 24: 91–96; Stjernswärd, Colleau, and Ventafridda, op. cit. 13 Blinderman, op. cit note 12. 4 II: DANIELS’ EXTENSION OF THE RAWLSIAN ACCOUNT Daniels’ account is the most developed Rawlsian position in relation to health and healthcare. Furthermore, Rawls endorses this view on several occasions.14 Thus, Daniels’ account is the natural starting point for a discussion of Rawlsian justice in palliative care. Daniels admits that ‘Rawls’s index of primary goods seems to be too truncated once we drop the assumption that all people are normal. People with equal indices will not have equally good life prospects if they have different health-care needs’.15 To cater for this shortfall Daniels extends Rawls’ theory by including the institutions protecting people’s health among society’s basic institutions aimed at providing fair equality of opportunity.16 To see why, we must consider Daniels’ view on health. Daniels understands health deficits as deviations from normal functioning. Normal functioning for an individual is ‘the subset of the normal range their skills and talents make it reasonable for them to pursue’. 17 Health needs are defined objectively as ‘those things we need in order to maintain, restore or provide functional equivalents (where possible) to normal species functioning (for the appropriate reference class by gender and age)’.18 Daniels then ‘emphasize[s] a relationship between normal functioning and opportunity, one of the primary social goods’.19 If health deficits impede people’s opportunities then the institutions tasked with providing such opportunities should also restore people to 14 Rawls, Justice as Fairness, 175 n58; John Rawls. 2005. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press: 184. 15 N. Daniels. 1985. Just Health Care. New York: Cambridge University Press: 43; Norman Daniels. 2008. Just Health : Meeting Health Needs Fairly. New York: Cambridge University Press: 56. 16 Daniels, Just Health Care: 45; Daniels, Just Health: 57. For critiques of this application of Rawls, see F. M. Kamm. Health and Equality of Opportunity. The American Journal of Bioethics 2001: 1: 17–19. 17 Daniels, Just Health Care: 108. 18 Ibid., 32; Daniels, Just Health: 42. 19 Daniels. Equality of What: Welfare, Resources, or Capabilities?: 280. See also Daniels, Just Health Care: 34; N.Daniels. Justice, Health, and Healthcare. The American Journal of Bioethics 2001; 1: 3; Daniels, Just Health, 46. 5 normal functioning. Thus, according to Daniels, the prominence and importance of health arises through its impact on people’s opportunities.20 The relation between health and opportunities does not rely on the specification of health as normal functioning (as long as health deficits reduce opportunities). So even though much criticism of Daniels revolves around the plausibility of his view on health, this article does not dwell on that discussion.21 The above formulations are more or less consistently expressed throughout Daniels’ work. The most important recent development has been Daniels’ effort to underscore how health is influenced by social determinants outside what is traditionally understood as health care 22 and to develop a procedural answer23 on how to distribute resources when reasonable persons could disagree over whom to give priority to in a world of scarce resources. 24 We now turn to how Daniels’ extension of the Rawlsian approach fares in relation to palliative care. III. RAWLSIAN PALLIATIVE CARE The starting point for the discussion of Daniels’ view is that it has a clear focus on opportunities rather than wellbeing. Intuitively and certainly in relation to palliative care the impact of health on our life-plans and opportunities might be considered as a strange reason to provide care. Wouldn’t wellbeing on some dimension provide a more sensible rationale?25 Rawlsians, however, do not have this individualistic conception of the aim of society. For them, the restoration of normal functioning is a compelling 20 Daniels, Justice, Health, and Healthcare: 3,4. 21 For such discussion see N. Holtug. Equality and the Treatment-Enhancement Distinction. Bioethics 2011; 25: 137–44; E. Krag. Health as Normal Function: A Weak Link in Daniels’s Theory of Just Health Distribution. Bioethics 2013. doi:10.1111/bioe.12007; M. Lanoix. From Normal Species Functioning to Capabilities, Is It Enough?. The American Journal of Bioethics 2013; 13: 20–21. 22 Daniels, Justice, Health, and Healthcare: 2; Daniels, Just Health: 12, 17, 42. 23 N. Daniels. Rationing Fairly: Programmatic Considerations. Bioethics 1993; 7: 224–33; Daniels, Just Health. 24 While the former is widely accepted as an important development, the later has been criticized; see A. Friedman. Beyond Accountability for Reasonableness. Bioethics 2008; 22: 101–12; M. B. Mahowald. Why Retreat to Procedural Justice?. The American Journal of Bioethics 2001; 1: 25–26. 25 G. Sreenivasan. Opportunity Is Not the Key. The American Journal of Bioethics 2001; 1: 1b–2b. 6 rationale for compensation because, and only because, it is a means to the social and political objectives of securing people’s opportunities.26 The next subsections examine different problems which this raises for Daniels’ account. The first relates to the role of pain relief in treatment and the second to the rationale for providing pain relief for those who cannot be cured. Reducing pain in treatment In the delivery of medical treatment the role of pain relief differs. Sometimes treatment is painful and could thus be supplemented by medicaments or other initiatives to relieve pain. In other cases only some forms of available treatment are painful and pain might be one reason for preferring one treatment over another. It is interesting whether Daniels’ account, with its focus on opportunities, is able to justify taking the relief of pain into account. To see why we may doubt this, consider first a person for whom the available treatment is painful. If the treatment is able to effectively restore the person’s normal functioning, it is hard to see how an account justifying treatment based on its ability to restore normal functioning can argue that pain relief should be supplied as well (or at least that it should be provided free of charge). Aspirin, Codeine, Ibuprofen, Morphine, and Paracetamol, analgesics included on the WHO Model List of Essential Medicines, would not be provided in any such cases, however bad the pain.27 Or consider a situation where we can choose between two treatments, which are equally effective in restoring opportunities. They differ, however, in how painful they are to undergo. Suppose, for instance, that an invasive procedure has the same quality of outcome as an 26 Daniels, Equality of What: Welfare, Resources, or Capabilities?,: 284–285. 27 For the complete list, see WHO, “WHO Model List of Essential Medicines,” 2013, http://apps.who.int/iris/bitstream/10665/93142/1/EML_18_eng.pdf?ua=1. 7 alternative non-invasive procedure, with the exception that the former will bring severe post-surgery pain while the latter is painless. Daniels’ account is, in principle, indifferent as to whether that treatment is carried out in a painless or agonizing manner. Since both of these criticisms would surely reflect badly on Daniels’ account, we will discuss three possible answers to them. The first reply to be considered doubts the relevance of wellbeing in a healthcare context. Briefly considering the idea that wellbeing or welfare is a more plausible rationale than preserving opportunities, Daniels dismisses the idea, writing that ‘much health care affects quality of life in other ways, so the benefit of reducing pain and suffering is not general enough for our purposes’.28 But this reply addresses the claim that health care is provided solely to ease pain and suffering. However, that is not the present claim, which is rather that pain and suffering are (at the very least) factors among others to be taken into account when assigning healthcare. Furthermore, Daniels states that ‘some suffering, for example, some emotional suffering, though a cause for concern, does not obviously become a concern of justice’ (Daniels 1981, 169). But our claim leaves open the question of whether justice is concerned with all (human) suffering. We merely need to show some cases where pain and suffering are a matter of justice. The amount of avoidable pain the state chooses to inflict when administering medical treatment is very much a matter of justice. Some suffering may not be a matter of justice, but that is not simply because it falls into the category of suffering. Other considerations are needed to support that conclusion. We may think that Daniels’ example of emotional suffering would often not be a matter of justice because it is impermissible for the state to interfere with citizens’ private lives by, for instance, compensating jilted lovers. But the state is not acting outside its jurisdiction when it 28 N. Daniels. Health-Care Needs and Distributive Justice. Philosophy & Public Affairs 1981; 10: 169. 8 provides less painful rather than more painful treatment. Thus, these answers from Daniels are inadequate to uphold the view that pain and wellbeing are not a concern in these matters. Another type of answer available to Daniels would be to concede the importance of wellbeing, but claim that his account is compatible with taking pain reduction into account. Let’s examine some possible arguments for such compatibility. The first compatibility claim could be to submit that relieving pain is, in practice, often necessary for doctors in order to perform a given treatment. But this does not provide a reason to prefer the least painful treatment under the stipulation that we are choosing between equally efficient treatments. Furthermore, it is bizarre to say that the only reason doctors should ever prescribe painkillers is to make their job easier, rather than to ease pain itself, so this argument for relieving pain is not satisfactory. It could also be submitted, drawing on Rawls, that we should prevent pain to secure the ‘social bases of self-respect.’ This, however, also seems inadequate. In some cases persons may receive unnecessarily discomforting treatment from the state without feeling disrespected. Many patients do not have a full understanding of the treatments available for their condition, so they would not know that they had received a more painful than necessary treatment. If, for all they know, the state has done as well as it can for them, why would they feel disrespected? Moreover, even if they do know that there are less painful treatments available, it will probably also be known that the state consistently refuses to accept pain reduction as one of its goals, and is merely acting on its stated principle. Again, in such circumstances patients may well feel greatly discomforted but not disrespected. It could be further countered that in such cases, regardless of patients’ subjective feeling of being respected, an objective state of 9 disrespect is present.29 However, it seems highly doubtful that one could draw from Daniels’ work an objective notion of disrespect that arose specifically in cases of avoidable pain given Daniels’ rejection of wellbeing as a measure of justice in healthcare. Thus, the second argument for the compatibility of Rawlsian justice with pain relief also fails. A final reply to the criticism is suggested by Blinderman. He argues that eliminating pain should be considered a part of protecting opportunities. On this account the issue has so far been discussed from the wrong perspective. Daniels need not argue that wellbeing or relief of pain is unimportant in the context of health care and he need not claim that protecting opportunities is compatible with the different concern of pain relief. Instead protecting opportunities includes providing the relief of pain. To illustrate why this is so Blinderman provides the following example of how this can be: As patients progress towards death their opportunities become profoundly limited. Nonetheless, we must acknowledge that one goal of palliative care is to preserve this limited opportunity range. Terminally ill patients may hope to communicate meaningfully with loved ones, reflect on their lives and finish a variety of projects. Such opportunities would be incompatible with pain and suffering. 30 For that reason he argues that Daniels’ account is very able to give us good reason to supply palliative care. He notes, however, one important limitation to that view: situations where we cannot bring people back to normal functioning.31 As this is 29 A referee suggested this response. 30 Blinderman, Palliative Care, Public Health and Justice: Setting Priorities in Resource Poor Countries: 107. 31 Ibid. 10 discussed in the next section, we can set that aside in order to assess whether Blinderman’s argument is plausible in the important context in which he offers it. The first thing that should be granted to the argument above is that since functioning is age-specific we can reasonably acknowledge that the palliative care in the example can be supplied by Daniels. This is so because it restores functioning in the relevant sense and can thus firmly be justified by the Rawlsian approach to health proposed by Daniels. We will not argue that it is stretching the concept of protecting opportunities. But we do argue that it is far from self-evident from the provided example that Daniels’ account can, in general, recommend palliative care. The reason for this is that in the example palliative care is the very thing restoring functioning and protecting opportunities. Surely, then, it can be incorporated into Daniels’ framework. But what happens when protecting opportunities and relieving pain come apart? Suppose a patient already has the ability to communicate with family and reflect on her life, but also suffers from severe pain. We can provide morphine, which will slightly reduce their overall ability to communicate and reflect, but will significantly reduce the pain.32 If the patient prefers to receive the morphine, we should surely provide it. But Daniels’ account cannot say this, as the morphine does nothing in terms of restoring opportunity – indeed, it slightly reduces opportunity through reducing the ability to communicate and reflect. The fundamental problem – the tension between the objectives of alleviating pain and protecting opportunities - resurfaces. Reducing pain - beyond treatment 32 See S. K Kamboj et al., The Effects of Immediate-Release Morphine on Cognitive Functioning in Patients Receiving Chronic Opioid Therapy in Palliative Care. Pain 2005; 117: 388–95. 11 Aside from whether Daniels’ account is able to provide palliative care as an integrated part of treatment, another important complication springs from the focus on restoring opportunities. There seem to be cases where the Rawlsian rationale developed by Daniels suggests care should not be provided at all.33 The thrust of the critique presented here is that if we allocate healthcare solely to restore ‘normal functioning’ in order to protect opportunities, many kinds of important palliative care initiatives should not be undertaken at all as they do not serve this purpose. On the face of it the Rawlsian idea of restoring people to the norm leaves those who cannot be so restored – who, we may hypothesise, are often the most ill – without any medical assistance.34 Consider Daniels’ statement that ‘if we can minimize the impact of the deficit on opportunities we have an obligation to do so…’.35 The critique is then straightforwardly to ask what we owe people when we cannot minimize the health impact on opportunities. When we are concerned with health deficits (or deviations from normal functioning) because of their impact on people’s opportunities, why should we then provide care for those whose opportunities we cannot bring back or improve? There is a fairly obvious response to this second problem. Daniels observes that ‘not all treatments are cures, and some institutions and services are needed to maintain persons in a way that is as close as possible to the idealization’,36 where idealization refers to normal functioning. Daniels labels such institutions a ‘third layer of institutions’, adding them to the layers aimed at preventing or curing disease. But this response is in clear tension with the objective of restoring normal functioning, as part of 33 Segall argues that this is also the case where measures outside the traditional health care setting do a better job of protecting opportunities and in cases where people of old age don’t have any life-plans left to pursue: Shlomi Segall. 2010. Health, Luck, and Justice. Princeton, NJ: Princeton: 32–36; 93. 34 A point which Blinderman concedes Blinderman, Palliative Care, Public Health and Justice: Setting Priorities in Resource Poor Countries: 107. 35 Daniels, Just Health: 148. 36 Daniels, Just Health Care: 48. 12 the activities of this ‘third layer of institutions’ will be to restore minor functionings which make it no easier to create or pursue life plans. For instance, pain relief may sometimes be neutral (or worse) regarding cognitive performance. Resources are thus allocated to activities with little or no influence on people’s opportunities in the Rawlsian sense. This problem is exacerbated when we consider what Daniels calls the fourth layer of institutions, which ‘involves health care and related social services for those who can in no way be brought closer to the idealization’.37 This seems to be where palliative care for those who cannot be cured is located. But here the tension between a justice-based rationale of restoring or protecting opportunities and the provision of care for those we cannot help in such a way is apparent. For if a patient is beyond the point at which we can bring them closer to normal functioning, it is clear that the objective of restoring normal functioning to protect opportunities cannot provide the rationale for their treatment. It is, then, very hard to see how Daniels can maintain that ‘all these institutions and services are needed if fair equality of opportunity is to be guaranteed’.38 None of the fourth layer activities will enable people to construct and act upon life plans. Freedom and opportunity in the Rawlsian senses will not in any way be expanded by the activities undertaken here. It would, as Daniels seems to agree, reflect badly on the Rawlsian theory of justice in health if such services cannot be provided in the name of justice. This would in effect leave Daniels’ account without the ability to justify palliative care. Stopping short of accepting that people whose opportunities we cannot improve should not be aided, two possibilities are seemingly open to the Rawlsian. One is to 37 Ibid. 38 Ibid.; Daniels, Just Health: 62. 13 present other reasons of justice for providing the care under discussion; the other is to point to values outside the scope of distributive justice able to secure the provision of such care. Considering the first possibility, wellbeing or welfare would be suitable candidates for this. But as should be clear from the earlier discussion this amounts to invoking non-Rawlsian reasons, and furthermore, to invoking reasons Daniels elsewhere considers not to be the right reasons for providing care. This approach raises a rather delicate question: if we prefer to go with provisions based on welfare rather than those based on opportunities when they differ in their recommendations, then why not use welfare from the outset? Thus this line of defence from the Rawlsian increases rather than decreases the extent to which we doubt that opportunities are the right focus. But perhaps Daniels and other Rawlsians need not introduce other justice values and furthermore need not to be embarrassed that their theory cannot justify the provision of palliative care to those whose opportunities we cannot improve. For as Daniels writes, ‘by the time we get to the fourth layer moral virtues other than justice become prominent’,39 or similarly, that ‘[t]hese services raise serious issues, for example about compassion and beneficence, that go beyond justice’.40 Although the word is not used, this appears to be a gesture towards charity. But non-restorative treatment cannot be left to the contingencies of charity. Some cases at least are unambiguously matters of justice and Daniels perhaps agrees when he asserts that ‘we owe people health care and related social services even when they cannot be brought closer to idealization’.41 While Daniels could say that those matters are of no concern to justice, 39 Daniels, Just Health Care: 48. 40 Daniels, Just Health: 62. 41 Ibid. 14 his hesitation to do so reveals that he does not consider this an attractive solution. We concur. The strength of the objections examined here and in the previous section, and the importance of the lack of suitable replies in Daniels’ framework can be illustrated by an example where they come together. Consider the case of cancer patients, often associated with palliative care. When the cancer is thought treatable, treatment will be provided in the most efficient way, regardless of how painful that may be. If the cancer turns terminal, any morphine publicly provided for instrumental reasons – to make medical procedures easier to perform – will be switched off, and the patient left in agony, if he cannot afford to pay for continued treatment and no charitable individual or organisation comes forward. Such cases show that, contrary to Daniels’ claim, it is simply not true in the context of the important areas of palliative care that an appropriate extension of Rawlsian theory accommodates egalitarian intuitions. The justificatory structure of Rawlsian justice, either orthodox or extended as Daniels proposes, leaves it indifferent to some kinds of overwhelmingly compelling medical need. IV. RAWLSIAN ALTERNATIVES Having considered Daniels’ account and found it unable to justify palliative care in a satisfying manner it might be worthwhile to consider alternative replies which could be used to address this discussion from a broader Rawlsian framework. The Rawlsian might, firstly, suggest that our claims have failed to account for the extent to which their favoured redistributive theory provides everyone with sufficient goods to secure their basic needs without the need for special provision. In particular, Rawls’ difference principle allocates income and wealth to the greatest benefit of the 15 least advantage. Under such an egalitarian distribution it could be thought sheer hyperbole to talk of cancer patients without morphine, especially given the fact that Rawlsian justice will compensate persons who do not receive the expected social primary goods owing to illnesses or accidents.42 Views along similar lines are also expressed by Daniels.43 We do not think this response is sound. It is simply not the case that Rawlsian redistribution provides for all the needs that it should. Certain medical treatments that may significantly decrease the amount of pain suffered by a patient may be beyond the means of some such persons even after redistribution. The Rawlsian compensation only provides for the loss of social primary goods, primarily income, and is insensitive to the cost of individual health care needs. The cost of an individual’s palliative care, even in an otherwise egalitarian society, may exceed the income they have lost due to illness. In that case the compensation they receive will be insufficient to meet their health care need. Even where the necessary treatments and aids are within the buying power of those who need them, it is simply unfair that the provision of such things should come out of their share of goods, leaving them with less money to spend on other things. Why, the egalitarian asks, should the ill have less money to spend on food, accommodation and other essential needs just because they are ill and want to be free of pain? In this regard more subjective ‘luck egalitarian’ distributive theories such as equality of resources, equality of opportunity for welfare and equality of access to advantage seem to be preferable, on account of their ability to take into account disadvantaging natural characteristics.44 42 Rawls, Justice as Fairness: 172–173. 43 N. Daniels, B. P Kennedy, and I. Kawachi. Why Justice Is Good for Our Health: The Social Determinants of Health Inequalities. Daedalus 1999; 128: 215–51; Daniels, Just Health: 94. 44 R. J. Arneson. Equality and Equal Opportunity for Welfare. Philosophical Studies 1989; 56: 77 – 93; G. A. Cohen. On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice. Ethics 1989; 99: 906–44; N. Eyal and A. Voorhoeve. Inequalities 16 A second Rawlsian response, like the first, aims to provide for palliative care through the difference principle. It differs from the first by adding health care to the list of social primary goods to be distributed by that principle, on the basis that health is something you want, whatever else you want.45 This seems a clear improvement on the standard Rawlsian theory as it provides a principled basis for providing palliative care where it does not further opportunity restoration. Yet it still falls short of what is required. Even if the list of primary goods relevant to justice were lengthened in this way, many of the inegalitarian effects of Rawlsian theory regarding health and healthcare would remain. As Allen Buchanan points out, Rawls proposes that principles are selected from behind a ‘veil of ignorance’ that would ‘preclude a solution to the problem of weighting health care against other primary goods because the answer will depend upon facts about the particular conditions of the society in which the notions in question are to be applied’ (Buchanan 1984: 61). Thus, the theory cannot guarantee any significant level of support for healthcare that does not restore opportunity as the decision regarding the weightings of particular primary goods would be left to politics to decide.46 This response does at least give palliative care representation within Rawlsian theory, but this may well amount to little in practice. The final Rawlsian response accepts that on the test of accounting for natural variations Rawlsian justice fails. But rather than adjust the theory, as the second in HIV Care: Chances Versus Outcomes. The American Journal of Bioethics 2011: 11: 42–44; Albertsen, A., and C. Knight. A Framework for Luck Egalitarianism in Health and Healthcare. Journal of Medical Ethics, February 6, 2014. doi:10.1136/medethics-2013-101666; Segall, op. cit. 45 Daniels writes that being in good health is not necessarily good for all of our goals, N. Daniels. Health-Care Needs and Distributive Justice. Philosophy & Public Affairs 1981;10: 154. Daniels remains sceptical towards such a strategy, mainly because it would allow for an inegalitarian distribution of healthcare: Daniels, Just Health Care, 43; Daniels, Just Health, 56.. On this point Rawls and Daniels disagree, for Rawls lists health as a natural primary good: Rawls, A Theory of Justice: 62. 46 A. E. Buchanan. The Right to a Decent Minimum of Health Care. Philosophy & Public Affairs 1984; 13: 62; R. M. Green. Access to Healthcare: Going Beyond Fair Equality of Opportunity. American Journal of Bioethics 2001; 1: 22–23. 17 response suggested, the third response insists that this shows the test to be incompatible with the Rawlsian requirement that theories of justice should be neutral between conceptions of the good. In other words, palliative care is not provided because to do so would prioritize some conceptions of the good (specifically, those that place some value on pain relief) over others. We have two comments on this response. First, were it true that palliative care was incompatible with the neutrality requirement, that would suggest nothing more than that this requirement is incompatible with egalitarianism. Second, we do not think it is true. Ronald Dworkin’s theory of equality of resources, for instance, acknowledges the neutrality requirement whilst being sensitive to natural variations.47 Furthermore, we can get further towards equality using primary goods than Rawls and Daniels manage. Allow us to return to the example of terminal cancer patients. The Rawlsian denies them their morphine on two dubious grounds: that absence of pain is not a primary social good, and they are the only things that get distributed; and that they are beyond any recovery to full membership of society. But is the benefit of being free of intense pain really only a conception of the good-relative benefit? Perhaps there are some flagellants who do not view this as a benefit; nonetheless, we feel confident that we could find as many, if not more, persons whose ends are not served by their possessing primary social goods such as wealth and power.48 We are inclined, then, to believe that absence of pain is at least as conception neutral as Rawls’ social primary goods. V. CONCLUSION 47 See R. Dworkin. 2000. Sovereign Virtue : The Theory and Practice of Equality. Cambridge Mass: Harvard Univ. Press. 48 See A. Schwartz. Moral Neutrality and Primary Goods. Ethics 1973; 83: 294–307; M. Teitelman. The Limits of Individualism. Journal of Philosophy 1972; 64, no. 18: 545–56. 18 In relation to the increasingly important topic of palliative care, it must be concluded that the Rawlsian project, as extended by Daniels, does not provide sound answers. Its inability to recommend the less painful treatment and its willingness to leave those who cannot be cured to the contingencies of charity is unacceptable. We believe this implication reflects badly on the enterprise of applying Rawlsian justice to health and health care. Those looking for a normative account of health care that accommodates palliative care should look elsewhere. work_ayyun2isvjge7lubtjjcboc7nm ---- Durham Research Online Deposited in DRO: 22 May 2008 Version of attached file: Published Version Peer-review status of attached file: Peer-reviewed Citation for published item: Beever, A. (2004) ’Aristotle on equity, law and justice.’, Legal theory., 10 (1). pp. 33-50. Further information on publisher’s website: http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S1352325204000163 Publisher’s copyright statement: 2004 Cambridge University Press Additional information: Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-profit purposes provided that: • a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • a link is made to the metadata record in DRO • the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Please consult the full DRO policy for further details. Durham University Library, Stockton Road, Durham DH1 3LY, United Kingdom Tel : +44 (0)191 334 3042 — Fax : +44 (0)191 334 2971 http://dro.dur.ac.uk CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by Durham Research Online https://core.ac.uk/display/66089?utm_source=pdf&utm_medium=banner&utm_campaign=pdf-decoration-v1 http://www.dur.ac.uk http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S1352325204000163 http://dro.dur.ac.uk/3245/ http://dro.dur.ac.uk/policies/usepolicy.pdf http://dro.dur.ac.uk Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-profit purposes provided that : a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source a link is made to the metadata record in DRO the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Durham University Library, Stockton Road, Durham DH1 3LY, United Kingdom Tel : +44 (0)191 334 3042 | Fax : +44 (0)191 334 2971 http://dro.dur.ac.uk Durham Research Online Deposited in DRO: 22 May 2008. Version of attached file: Published. Peer-review status of attached file: Peer-reviewed. Citation for published item: Beever, A. (2004) 'Aristotle on equity, law and justice.' , Legal theory., 10 (1), pp. 33- 50. Further information on publisher’s website: http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S1352325204000163 Legal Theory, 10 (2004), 33–50. Printed in the United States of America Published by Cambridge University Press 0361-6843/04 $12.00 + 00 ARISTOTLE ON EQUITY, LAW, AND JUSTICE* Allan Beever University of Auckland I. INTRODUCTION In a famous passage in his Ethics, Aristotle considers the nature of equity and its relation to justice.1 His conclusion seems to be that equity’s role is to prevent the law from adhering too rigidly to its own rules and principles when those rules and principles produce injustice. Hence equity permits judges to depart from legal principle in order to promote justice. In this ar- ticle, however, I argue that this conclusion is problematic as it is inconsistent with other claims Aristotle makes, both in his short discussion of equity in the Ethics and elsewhere. Accordingly, I suggest a reinterpretation of Aris- totle’s view that explains more satisfactorily the connection between law, in its various senses, and justice. II. FORMS AND KINDS OF JUSTICE For Aristotle, “justice” has both a particular and a general meaning. In its general sense, it is a synonym for virtue; the just man being the virtuous or good man. Conversely, in its more particular sense, the only sense with which we are interested here, justice is concerned with only part of virtue: giving persons their due. Aristotle maintains that particular justice has two forms: distributive and corrective.2 He also describes a kind of justice—legal justice—and identifies equity in relation to both legal justice and particular justice. * I would like to thank John Gardner and the anonymous reviewer for Legal Theory. 1. ARISTOTLE, ETHICS, 198–200 [1137a32–1138a3] (J.A.K. Thomson, trans., 1976). See also Aristotle, Rhetoric, in ARISTOTLE: THE COMPLETE WORKS 2152, 2188 [1374a25–b23] (Jonathan Barnes ed., 1984). I adopt Thompson’s translation of the Ethics for the most part because it is most friendly to the view I argue against. 2. The translation is often “commutative justice” or “rectificatory justice.” I choose to adopt “corrective justice” as that is the term most familiar to lawyers. In the following, I ignore the problem that it is unclear whether criminal law belongs to distributive or corrective justice on this schema. 33 34 ALLAN BEEVER In order to understand the relationship of these concepts, it is necessary to comprehend the distinction between forms or species of justice3 and what I refer to as kinds or types of justice. There are many kinds of justice. Aristotle focuses on legal justice and political justice, but there are many others: justice within the family,4 between academic colleagues, and so on. Justice comes in kinds because the content of justice varies with respect to different activities.5 Justice in the home is different from justice amongst one’s colleagues. Nevertheless, all kinds of justice are species of the overar- ching particular justice—I refer to this here as “absolute justice.” Hence one action may be just from the perspective of one kind of justice, unjust from the perspective of another, but absolutely just or unjust. Imagine that I have a son and a daughter and that my daughter is one of my students. If I spend much time on all of my students then, as a matter of distributive academic justice (if we can speak of such), I may be obliged to spend time with my daughter that means that I cannot spend an equal amount of time with my son. But this may be said to be inconsistent with distributive parental justice. Nevertheless, it will be possible to say that some action—likely to be some sort of compromise—is absolutely distributively just. On the other hand, the forms of justice correspond to general methods of evaluating justice: either in terms of the overall spread of “honour or money or such other assets as are divisible among members of the community” (dis- tributive justice) or in terms of rectifying “the conditions of a transaction” (corrective justice).6 Hence there are only two forms of justice. At least in theory, there are some actions to which neither form of justice applies: those that do not distribute honor, money, or other relevant assets and do not involve gains and losses in transactions. Other actions involve one form of justice, and some involve both. With respect to that last set of actions, distributive and corrective justice may come into conflict. For instance, an action may be correctively unjust but distributively just (stealing from the rich to give to the poor?) or vice versa. In such circumstances, it is impossible to say that the action is just or unjust overall. There is no overall form of justice that captures both distributive and corrective justice. Hence, while such an action may be good or bad overall—because, say, the distributive justice is more important than the corrective injustice—we cannot say that it is absolutely just or unjust. Accordingly, there are two forms of absolute justice: absolute distributive justice and absolute corrective justice. In cases in which only one type of jus- tice is relevant, this presents no difficulty. However, in cases involving both forms of justice, the conflict between distributive and corrective justice is im- portant and, as discussed below, relates to Aristotle’s doctrine of equity. For the sake of simplicity and clarity, I postpone that discussion for the moment 3. ARISTOTLE, NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, 70 [1130b30–131a1] (Terence Irwin, trans., 1999). 4. ARISTOTLE, ETHICS, supra note 1, at 189 [1134b10–13]. 5. Id. 6. Id. at 176–177 [1130b30–1131a1]. Aristotle on Equity, Law, and Justice 35 and assume that the cases under investigation involve actions that are relevant either to distributive justice or to corrective justice but not to both. III. JUSTICE AND EQUITY One consequence of the above is that legal justice is not absolute justice (distributive or corrective) but is the kind of justice appropriate to the activity of doing law, in a sense to be elucidated below. In consequence, Aristotle maintains that legal justice exhibits certain deficiencies from the perspective of absolute justice. One reason for this is that “all law is universal, and there are some things about which it is not possible to pronounce rightly in general terms.”7 The latter claim is a product of Aristotle’s view that in ethics “we must be satisfied with a broad outline of the truth; that is, in arguing about what is for the most part so from premises which are for the most part true we must be content to draw conclusions that are similarly qualified.”8 We may summarize this by saying that for Aristotle, ethical truth is too complex to be captured by any finite consistent set of principles. Hence a system that insisted on the observation of principles could not realize justice. Here, then, we can see why Aristotle would hold that legal justice cannot perfectly map onto absolute justice. As “all law is universal”—that is, as all law is expressed in terms of universal principles—it is guaranteed to generate unjust results in some cases. Equity fills the gap between legal justice and absolute justice. The content of equity consists of those judgments required to reconcile the former with the latter. Say that legal justice dictates that A is bound to do X but it is (all things considered) unjust to require A to do X. Legal justice is that part of morality that dictates that A is to do X; absolute justice is the part that permits A not to do X; and equity is the part that acts on legal justice to restrict its operation so that A does not in fact have to do X. Equity, then, is not justice itself but the part of morality that corrects the deficiencies of legal justice. [W]hen the law states a general rule, and a case arises under this that is ex- ceptional, then it is right, where the legislator owing to the generality of his language has erred in not covering that case, to correct the omission by a ruling such as the legislator himself would have given if he had been present there, and as he would have enacted if he had been aware of the circumstances.9 In a recent exploration of this view, John Gardner maintains that this implies an essential separation between law and justice. Because law must be expressed too generally to map onto absolute justice, “the fact that they ought to be just . . . tells against legal systems being too true to their ruly 7. Id. at 199 [1137b14–17] (reference omitted). 8. Id. at 64 [1094b20–23]. 9. Id. at 199 [1137b20–24]. 36 ALLAN BEEVER natures.”10 He insists that equity permits judges to depart from law in order to realize justice: equity is justice’s rebellion against law.11 In the following, I refer to this as “the doctrine of equitable discretion.” The notion is that Aristotle argues that judges have the authority to depart from legal justice and from legal rules on the basis of equity. According to Gardner, there- fore, Aristotle does not accept the view of legal formalists that “grotesquely self-congratulatory doctrine that law, so long as it remains true to its own distinctive form, cannot but be just.”12 IV. PROBLEMS A. Legal Justice The claim that equity permits judges to depart from legal justice in order to realize absolute justice makes the interpretation of legal justice problematic. What is legal justice? The intuitive answer is that it is the justice enforced in courts of law. But, given the doctrine of equitable discretion, courts of law do not enforce legal justice. Rather, due to the operation of equity, the courts implement absolute justice. What, then, is legal justice? One answer is provided by translating these issues into the language of the common law. According to this view, legal justice is the justice applicable to the common law, equity is the justice applicable to Equity,13 and absolute justice is the result of the combination of common law and Equity. But this solution trades inappropriately on the peculiar meanings of the words “law” and “Equity” in the common law. For common lawyers, “law” and “common law” have two relevant meanings. Speaking roughly, the terms relate either to the decisions of courts minus the application of Equity or simply to the decisions of courts. One might say that law equals law plus Equity. But these distinctions were of no significance in ancient Greece. For Aristotle, “law” cannot refer to what we call law-as-in-law-minus-Equity; rather, it must refer to what we call law-as-in-law-plus-Equity. The conclusion must be that legal justice is not the justice that the law enforces; but without explanation, that is a curious position. A second answer to our question is that legal justice is synonymous with the positive law or perhaps with a coherent account of the positive law. On 10. John Gardner, The Virtue of Justice and the Character of Law, 53 CURRENT LEGAL PROBS. 1, 18 (2000). 11. Id. at 16. At least, this must be Gardner’s argument if it is to connect with the views he intends to attack. For instance, though he rejects Weinrib’s formalism, that theory does not apply to issues such as law reform outside the courtroom. See, e.g., ERNEST J. WEINRIB, THE IDEA OF PRIVATE LAW 70, 210–211 (1995). For similar interpretations of Aristotle to Gardner’s, see, e.g., Larry A. DiMatteo, The History of Natural Law Theory: Transforming Embedded Influences into a Fuller Understanding of Modern Contract Law, 60 U. PITT. L. REV. 839 (1999); Richard W. Wright, The Principles of Justice, 75 NOTRE DAME L. REV. 1859 (2000); Emily Sherwin, Restitution and Equity: An Analysis of The Principle of Unjust Enrichment, 79 TEXAS L. REV. 2083 (2001). 12. Gardner, supra note 10, at 12. Gardner’s chief target here is Ernest Weinrib. 13. For clarity I capitalize “Equity” when referring to the area of Anglo-American law. Aristotle on Equity, Law, and Justice 37 this view we might say, in the language of the modern common law, that legal justice equates with precedent or with extant legal principle, and the role of equity is to reform the law—through judicial overruling, legislation, and so on—so that legal justice (the positive law) better reflects absolute justice. On this interpretation, it is easy to see why Gardner would regard legal formalism as “grotesquely self-congratulatory.”14 If the form of the law cor- responds to legal justice, and legal justice is identified with the positive law, then the formalist claims that the positive law must be just whatever it is. Clearly, Gardner is right that this is not Aristotle’s view. However, the idea that legal justice equates with the positive law does not sit well with Aristotle’s discussion. For Aristotle, the various kinds of justice are not merely descriptions of beliefs about justice or conventional accounts of virtue. Rather, the kinds of justice are parts of virtue. Accordingly, unless we have good reason to do otherwise, “legal justice” should be read as referring to the way that the law should be, not necessarily to the way that it is. Legal justice is the justice that the law should instantiate. Moreover, it is impossible to understand Aristotle’s claim that legal justice dictates that law be expressed in general terms15 on the reading that legal justice equates with the positive law. Aristotle maintains that, when the law is too general to capture absolute justice, “the law is none the less right; because the error lies not in the law nor in the legislator, but in the nature of the case.”16 But if legal justice was synonymous with the positive law, then surely it would follow that legal justice is at least occasionally inappropriately general. Consequently, the exploration of legal justice must be read as an examination of the natural law and not merely a reflection of the positive law of some society.17 This demonstrates that even were Gardner right to identify the form of the law with legal justice, in an important sense “so long as it remains true to its own distinctive form [the law] cannot but be just.”18 On Gardner’s reading, the law’s form is legal justice, which is a kind of justice according to Aristotle, though it is to some extent deficient.19 More important, if the doctrine of equitable discretion were correct, then it would be unintuitive to regard the form of the law as corresponding to legal justice. For a legal formalist, the law’s form dictates how judges should decide cases.20 Hence, accepting the doctrine of equitable discretion, the 14. Gardner, supra note 10, at 12. 15. Supra note 1, at 199 [1137b20–24]. 16. Id. at 199 [1137b15–20]. 17. Cf. Tony Burns, Aristotle and Natural Law, 19 HIST. POL. THOUGHT 142, 162–166 (1998) (exploring Aristotle’s natural law theory). 18. Gardner, supra note 10, at 12. 19. It may appear incoherent to argue that a kind of justice can be deficient: If it is deficient, then it is not justice. However, it must be recalled that legal justice, like political justice, is the justice relevant to some kind of activity. In Aristotle’s view, the justice relevant to some types of activity may be appropriate to that activity but to some extent inconsistent with absolute justice. See infra, text accompanying notes 43–59, 67. 20. Weinrib, supra note 11, at ch. 2. 38 ALLAN BEEVER form of the law could relate only to legal justice plus equity and not to legal justice alone. On this approach, legal formalism does not appear at all “grotesquely self-congratulatory”;21 ironically, it appears to match Gardner’s own view.22 The above leads to a third answer to our question as to the nature of legal justice. Perhaps the idea is that legal rules should be generated according to legal justice. However, as no rules of any kind can perfectly capture absolute justice, courts are permitted to depart from legal rules when they are incon- sistent with legal justice. This seems to be Gardner’s view in arguing that “the fact that they ought to be just . . . tells against legal systems being too true to their ruly natures.”23 On its face, this asserts that it is in the nature of the law to depart from its own nature. However, Gardner should be taken to mean that courts should not be bound by legal rules, even if those rules equate to justice as closely as it is possible for rules to do. On this view, legal rules are generalizations true for the most part24 and hence are not binding on judges. However, while these “rules” may serve to remind judges of salient moral considerations and may give an appearance of predictability to the law, as they are in no way binding, it seems odd to describe them as legal rules. Moreover, on this view, legal justice is the kind of justice that underlies legal “rules.” But legal rules do not oblige courts of law and hence do not capture the justice that the law actually enforces. Though this is not incoherent, one would have thought that legal justice was more important and had more to do with the decisions of courts than that. I conclude that the interpretation under examination cannot readily ex- plain the nature of legal justice. B. Law and Arbitration The second problem with the notion that Aristotle argues in favor of eq- uitable discretion is the following. Almost immediately after the quotation above, thought to assert that judges may depart from law on the basis of equity,25 Aristotle goes on to say that “[t]his in fact is also the reason why everything is not regulated by law: it is because there are some cases that no law can be framed to cover, so that they require special ordinance.”26 If Aristotle argues for the doctrine of equitable discretion, then it is hard to know what to make of this. Aristotle appears to claim that some areas of human life are ill suited to regulation by law because they are so complex that justice with respect to them cannot be captured by universal principles. 21. Gardner, supra note 10, at 12. 22. Id. at 18. 23. Id. 24. Cf. John McDowell, Virtue and Reason, 62 MONIST 331, 336 (1979) (exploring the nature of moral “rules” in Aristotle’s thought). 25. See supra, text accompanying note 9. 26. Supra note 1, at 200 [1137b28–29]. Aristotle on Equity, Law, and Justice 39 But this is meant to be true of all areas of human life. Moreover, if equity is capable of remedying the law’s inflexibility, then what is the problem? If equity permits judges to depart from legal justice when it is inconsistent with absolute justice, then it should follow that no area of human life is too complex to be regulated by law with a larger or smaller dose of equity.27 However, perhaps Aristotle meant to argue that some areas of human life are so complex that it is impossible to fashion laws with respect to them that approximate justice even for the most part. For an unstated reason, this may be said to lead to the conclusion that law should not regulate in these areas. Hence the suggestion is that Aristotle’s considered position is that it may be appropriate for law to regulate those areas of human life in which justice is capable of being closely approximated by general principle— though general principle will never completely capture justice in any area of life—while law must refrain from regulating those areas of life in which general principle cannot even approximate justice. However, it is worth remembering that this is not what Aristotle actually says. Moreover, it is not clear that the reply succeeds. Rather, the correct conclusion seems to be that in complex areas of life it is equity rather than law that should do most of the actual governing. Hence Aristotle’s conclusion that these areas require governance by “special ordinance” does not follow, as the judicial enforcement of equity is supposed to be de rigueur. For this reason, this reading cannot make sense of Aristotle’s distinction between legal decision-making and arbitration. An “arbitrator goes by the equity of a case, a judge by the law, and arbitration was invented with the express purpose of securing full power for equity.”28 But according to the doctrine of equitable discretion, this is no less true in law. On this view, a judge too goes by the equity of the case: equity trumps. For Aristotle, the distinction between judging and arbitrating involves a difference in kind, but on the view expressed here it is at most a difference in degree. C. Law Is General Principle The above discussion also begs the following question—our third problem: If courts are permitted to depart from legal rules when they conflict with absolute justice, why does Aristotle insist that the law be expressed in terms of general rules? Of course it is possible to invent reasons—for example, to give 27. Of course, there may be reasons other than complexity why the law should not regulate in certain areas: privacy, liberty, etc. This is of no relevance to this argument and is in any event not mentioned by Aristotle. 28. Aristotle,Rhetoric, supra note 1, at 2188 [1374a18–1374b23]. J.A.K. Thompson suggests that when Aristotle refers to judges, he intends arbitrators. ARISTOTLE, ETHICS, supra note 1, at 180, note 2. However, this is mistaken. In contemporary Athens, judges were jurors repre- sentative of the citizenry as a whole, whose role was to enforce law. Arbitration was a separate matter. For instance, in private cases, arbitration was an alternative dispute resolution mecha- nism available to parties who could agree on an arbitrator. RUSS VERSTEEG, LAW IN THE ANCIENT WORLD 203–204, 214–216 (2002). 40 ALLAN BEEVER the law a veneer of predictability—but these arguments are not Aristotle’s. Moreover, in the Politics Aristotle insists: it is impossible that all things should be precisely set down in writing; for enactments must be universal, but actions are concerned with particulars. Hence we infer that sometimes and in certain cases laws should be changed; but when we look at the matter from another point of view, great caution would seem to be required. For the habit of lightly changing the laws is an evil, and, when the advantage is small, some errors both of lawgivers and rulers had better be left . . . .29 This caution is in tension with the notion that judges are free to depart from legal rules whenever they generate injustice. First, if the legislator must not alter legislation, even when there is a small advantage in doing so, why is it appropriate for judges routinely to depart from law on the basis of equity? Second, it is not clear why small changes in the law are required at all. If judges may depart from law on the basis of equity, then small, perhaps even large, alterations to the law may effectively be made by judges. Further: The advocates of kingship maintain that the laws speak only in general terms, and cannot provide for circumstances; and that for any science to abide by written rules is absurd . . . . Hence it is clear that a government acting according to written laws is plainly not the best. Yet surely the ruler cannot dispense with the general principle which exists in law . . . .30 Although Aristotle is not expressing his own view as to the desirability of kingship in this passage—Aristotle appears prepared to accept kingship if it is clear that the king is significantly superior in virtue and wisdom to the citizens31—it is clear that Aristotle is of the view that if a society opts for the rule of law rather than the rule of man, then rulers must utilize general principle. But if that is true of the rulers, then surely it must also be true of judges. Moreover, given Aristotle’s supposed attachment to equitable discretion, his claim that the law must be expressed in terms of legal rules seems inco- herent. According to the doctrine of equitable discretion, the law in fact is not capable of being expressed in terms of general rules.32 Certainly, legal rules are capable of being so expressed, but these are mere guidelines, rules of thumb, rather than rules proper. The conclusion seems therefore to be, 29. ARISTOTLE, THE POLITICS AND THE CONSTITUTION OF ATHENS, 49 [1269a10–16] (B. Jowett, trans., 1996) (hereinafter “POLITICS”). 30. Id. at 85–86 [1286a10–16]. 31. Id. at 87 [1286b9–21]. But see ETHICS, supra note 1, at 188 [1134a35–1134b3] (arguing that the rule of law is to be preferred). 32. Remembering that we are not entitled to help ourselves to the jurisdictional distinction between law and Equity. Aristotle on Equity, Law, and Justice 41 despite Aristotle’s explicit claims to the contrary, that law is not capable of being expressed in general principles. D. The Equitable Man Finally, the doctrine of equitable discretion seems inconsistent with Aris- totle’s description of the equitable man. The equitable man “is one who chooses and does equitable acts, and is not unduly insistent upon his rights, but accepts less than his share, although he has the law on his side.”33 The equitable man is one who does not always stand on his rights. But what are his rights? The answer seems to be his entitlements according to legal justice. But that answer is unsatisfactory. If courts enforce absolute justice rather than legal justice, then there is no right to legal justice. The answer implausibly implies that one has a legal right to something that a court will not and should not enforce. Moreover, Aristotle claims that the equitable man has law on his side, rather than on the side of justice. But again, this seems to make sense only if we anachronistically rely on a jurisdictional distinction between law and Equity. We have seen, then, that there are serious problems with the idea that Aris- totle accepts the doctrine of equitable discretion. His view of the relation- ship between equity, justice, and law must be more complex and nuanced than suggested. In the following section, I propose an alternative reading of Aristotle’s view designed to avoid the problems encountered above. V. SOLUTIONS A. Legal Justice If legal justice is not the justice that should motivate judges, then what is it? Despite the tendency of common lawyers to read Aristotle otherwise,34 I submit that his answer is clear: legal justice is the kind of justice appropriate to legislation.35 For Aristotle, then, legal justice applies not to judges but to legislators; it is not a judicial justice but a legislative justice. Hence Aristotle says that equity is: the sort of justice which goes beyond the written law. Its existence partly is and partly is not intended by legislators; not intended, where they have noticed no defect in the law; intended, where they find themselves unable to define things exactly, and are obliged to legislate universally where matters hold only for the most part; or where it is not easy to be complete owing to the endless 33. ETHICS, supra note 1, at 200 [1137b35–1138a3]. 34. See supra note 11. 35. See also John E. Pattantyus, Aristotle’s Doctrine of Equity, 51 MODERN SCHOOLMAN 213, 217 (1974). 42 ALLAN BEEVER possible cases presented, such as the kinds and sizes of weapons that may be used to inflict wounds—a lifetime would be too short to make out a complete list of these. If, then, a precise statement is impossible and yet legislation is necessary, the law must be expressed in wide terms; and so, if a man has no more than a finger-ring on his hand when he lifts it to strike or actually strikes another man, he is guilty of a criminal act according to the written words of the law; but he is innocent really, and it is equity that declares him to be so.36 And when he discusses the role of equity in remedying this error, he main- tains that: when the law states a general rule, and a case arises under this that is ex- ceptional, then it is right, where the legislator owing to the generality of his language has erred in not covering that case, to correct the omission by a ruling such as the legislator himself would have given if he had been present there, and as he would have enacted if he had been aware of the circumstances.37 The claim, then, is not that law in general—including our common law (here meaning common law as opposed to statute law)—corresponds to legal justice from which judges may depart. Rather, the notion is that leg- islators should be motivated by legal justice, although it is understood that legislation will be overly general: in cases where it is necessary to make a general pronouncement, but impossible to do so rightly, the law takes account of the majority of cases, though not unaware that in this way errors are made. And the law is none the less right; because the error lies not in the law nor in the legislator, but in the nature of the case . . . .38 Because of this understanding, judges are permitted to depart from a lit- eral interpretation of legislation when it is clear that such would produce a result that the legislators would not have intended.39 There are two relevant circumstances. First, the legislators may have passed legislation that would produce a result that they would not have intended if interpreted literally in circumstances that they did not consider. Here, Aristotle argues that judges may interpret the legislation more flexibly to reflect the intentions the leg- islators would have had had they turned their minds to such circumstances. Second, the legislators may have known that in a certain circumstances the legislation interpreted literally would work injustice, but may have been 36. Rhetoric, supra note 1, at 2188 [1374a18–1374b23]. 37. ETHICS, supra note 1, at 199 [1137b20–24]. 38. Id. at 199 [1137b15–18]. 39. Cf. ZIVILGESETZBUCH art. 1 (Switzerland). “In the absence of an applicable legal provision, the judge pronounces in accordance with customary law and, in the absence of a custom, according to the rules that he would establish if he had to act as legislator.” The content of legal justice is discussed infra notes 49, 55. Aristotle on Equity, Law, and Justice 43 unable to frame the legislation to avoid this. In such circumstances, Aristo- tle maintains that judges may realize the actual intentions of the legislators rather than their intentions as literally expressed in the legislation. The role of equity in law, then, is to realize the intentions of the legislator not cap- tured by the general principles expressed in the legislation. As we would say, equity directs attention to the spirit rather than to the letter of the law. Note that this does not mean that judges have the power to interpret statutes in the light of absolute justice. Aristotle’s claim is only that judges may attempt to realize the intent of the legislator, given that that intent will not and cannot be captured in the form that legislation must take. This, then, is far from the view that equity is justice’s rebellion against law. B. Law Is General Principle That equity in law is a principle of statutory interpretation also explains Aris- totle’s endorsement for societies governed by the rule of law of the claim that “surely the ruler cannot dispense with the general principle which exists in law.”40 This is not an assertion of a moral principle—an assertion com- pletely unsupported by argument—but rather the following practical point. If a society is governed by more than one person, then a decision-making procedure must be found for determining the decisions that are to govern the society. The content of these decisions cannot be discovered merely by asking any one individual. Hence the decisions must be expressed in some ob- jective manner. In practice, this means that decisions must be expressed in legislation, and legislation must be expressed in terms of general principles, there being no other way of writing it. Seeing that Aristotle’s discussion of equity in law is focused on legislation allows us to solve two of our problems: the meaning of legal justice and the need for law, meaning legislation, to be expressed in terms of general principle. Two problems remain. These are understanding the equitable man and the claim that some areas of life must be governed by arbitration rather than by law. These are solved by shifting our attention away from law. C. The Equitable Man To whom is Aristotle’s discussion of equity directed? The usual answer is that it is directed at the judge: Aristotle is concerned to elucidate appropriate ju- dicial decision-making. No doubt this is one of Aristotle’s aims, as discussed earlier in this section. However, it is not his sole objective. Recall that Aris- totle’s discussion of equity occurs in the context of a examination of virtue. The goal of the Ethics is not to provide a theory of law or of politics (at least as we understand the latter term), but to present an account of how citizens 40. POLITICS, supra note 29, at 86 [1286a15–16]. 44 ALLAN BEEVER should live their lives. The focus, then, is not solely on the role of equity in law but also on its place in ordinary life. In particular, the discussion is concerned with the role equity plays in making a person just. This becomes more apparent if we turn from J.A.K. Thompson’s translation of Aristotle’s passage on the equitable man to Terence Irwin’s. “It is also evident from this who the decent person is; for he is the one who decides on and does such actions, not an exact stickler for justice in the bad way, but taking less than he might even though he has the law on his side.”41 First, note that Irwin chooses the term “decency” rather than “equity,” making clear that the focus is not on judges in courtrooms but on citizens in their daily lives. It is also clear that the equitable or decent man is one who accepts less than the law will give him. This does not mean that he takes less than legislation would have given him were it not for the principles of statutory interpretation (i.e., equity in law). It means what it says: the equitable man is one who sometimes declines to enforce his legal rights. In order to see why this would be, it is necessary to examine further Aristotle’s view of the connection between justice and law. i. Distributive Justice and the Law As indicated above, Aristotle distinguishes between distributive justice and corrective justice. Unsurprisingly, he argues that the content of the former is essentially political. This is because distributive justice relies on a conception of equality that is politically controversial.42 Thus: Everyone agrees that justice in distribution must be in accordance with merit in some sense, but they do not all mean the same kind of merit: the democratic view is that the criterion is free birth; the oligarchic that it is wealth or good family; the aristocratic that it is excellence.43 Accordingly, Aristotle is unable to elucidate the content of distributive justice in the Ethics. That task must await a full exploration of political justice in the Politics. In Aristotle’s view, the aim of politics is to produce virtue and thereby happiness in citizens.44 However, Aristotle recognizes that people disagree as to the content of virtue and happiness; hence people disagree as to the ap- propriate content of politics. Aristotle describes this dispute as conflict over the constitution45 and characterizes the dispute as related to distributive 41. NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, supra note 3, at 84 [1137b35–1138a3]. The interpretation I offer in the following does not rely specifically on this translation, though this translation is more suggestive than others. 42. ETHICS, supra note 1, at 177–178 [1131a20–25]. 43. Id. at 178 [1131a25–29]. 44. POLITICS, supra note 29, at 13 [1252b29–30]. Compare TERENCE IRWIN, ARISTOTLE’S FIRST PRINCIPLES 425 (1988) (arguing that Aristotle’s theory is ambiguous as to whether politics aims for the good of society as a whole or for the good of each individual). 45. The remainder of POLITICS deals with how the constitution is best implemented in practice. Aristotle on Equity, Law, and Justice 45 justice.46 In the Politics, Aristotle elucidates and defends his conception of the best constitution. Nevertheless, Aristotle insists that “the best is often unattainable, and therefore the true legislator and statesman ought to be acquainted, not only with that which is best in the abstract, but also with that which is best relatively to circumstances.”47 Hence, although ideally all states should adopt the best constitution, Aristotle recognizes that this is impractical and that in practice states should adopt the best constitutions they are able to adopt.48 Aristotle also insists that the laws of the state that relate to distributive justice should reflect the constitution as it is rather than an ideal constitution. “[T]he laws are, and ought to be, framed with a view to the constitution.”49 This means that a society’s laws may not and in fact are unlikely to capture absolute distributive justice. Accordingly, with respect to these laws, the eq- uitable man is the one who declines to enforce in his favor the laws that instantiate the constitution’s conception of distributive justice when such enforcement would conflict with distributive justice as it is in fact. For instance, imagine that a state with an oligarchic constitution passes a law that generates an obligation in the poor to serve the wealthy. Assume also that democracy, rather than oligarchy, is consistent with absolute distributive justice. Hence, while the law in question is compatible with the constitution, it is inconsistent with absolute distributive justice. In such circumstances, an equitable wealthy man would decline to enforce that law in his favor. He would do so because, while he recognizes that the law is in accordance with the conception of distributive justice captured in the constitution, he also recognizes that the law is incompatible with absolute distributive justice. Hence he takes “less than he might even though he has law on his side.”50 It is important to note that it does not follow that a judge is permitted to refuse to enforce that law. To do so would be to undermine the notion that a state is governed in accordance with its constitution. Were the equitable man to find himself a judge, he would be obliged to enforce the law.51 ii. Corrective Justice and the Law As indicated above, Aristotle is unable to give an account of the content of distributive justice in the Ethics as he recognizes that that form of justice is inescapably political. On the other hand, Aristotle does provide an account 46. POLITICS supra note 29, at 73 [1280a7–22]; Francisco L. Lisi, The Concept of Law in Aristotle’s Politics, in 16 PROC. BOSTON AREA COLLOQUIUM ANCIENT PHIL., 29, 40–41 (John J. Cleary & Gary M. Gurtler, eds., 2001). 47. POLITICS, supra note 29, at 92 [1288b25–28]. 48. Id. at 92–93 [1288b34–1289a25]. 49. Id. at 92 [1289a13–15]. The constitution, then, determines the content of distributive legal justice. 50. NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, supra note 3, at 84 [1138a2–3]. 51. Similar points have led some to conclude that Aristotle was a legal positivist; see, e.g., Hans Kelsen, Aristotle’s Doctrine of Justice, in WHAT IS JUSTICE? JUSTICE, LAW, AND POLITICS IN THE MIRROR OF SCIENCE: COLLECTED ESSAYS 110, 125–136 (2000). For discussion, see Burns, supra note 17, at 162–166. 46 ALLAN BEEVER of the content of corrective justice in the Ethics. He is able to do so be- cause the concept of equality operative in corrective justice is not politically controversial.52 Hence, for example, “it makes no difference whether a good man has defrauded a bad one or vice versa, nor whether a good man or a bad one has committed adultery; all that the law considers is the difference caused by the injury.”53 Therefore the focus of corrective justice “is restricted and retrospective; it does not consider either the common good, or even the principles of distributive justice, but considers only the harm that has been done and the means of restoring the status quo ante.”54 Accordingly, for Aris- totle, the content of corrective justice is apolitical and does not depend on the constitution.55 Now, Aristotle clearly believes that some areas of law appropriately in- stantiate corrective justice.56 As the content of corrective justice does not depend on politics or on the nature of the constitution, legal justice with respect to those laws that instantiate corrective justice is coextensive with absolute corrective justice. Hence in this area the equitable man cannot be one who declines to enforce his legal rights because he recognizes that they do not correspond to justice in fact. Here, then, an alternative explanation of the equitable man is required. One must recall that corrective justice is only part of justice. Accordingly, the areas of law governed by corrective justice may conflict with distributive justice. Moreover, modern experience has taught us that this conflict will occur frequently. A good example of this clash between the forms of justice can be observed in the decision of the House of Lords in Bolton v. Stone.57 Members of the defendant cricket club were playing against a visiting team when one of the visitors drove the ball out of the ground and onto an adjacent little-used road. The ball struck and injured the plaintiff. The court estimated that a ball was driven out of the ground on average once every five years. The House of Lords ruled that as the chance of injury was so low, the defendant was not negligent. However, the cricket club had paid damages to the plaintiff after it had been found liable in negligence by the Court of Appeal, and the club made no effort to recover those damages after the decision of the House of Lords. This is sometimes taken as evidence that the common law is out of step with justice.58 For Aristotle, this conclusion is simplistic. The common law may be entirely consistent with absolute corrective justice and 52. ETHICS, supra note 1, at 180 [1132a5–6]. 53. Id. at 180 [1132a1–6] (emphasis added). 54. Irwin, supra note 44, at 429. 55. Hence the content of corrective legal justice is absolute corrective justice itself. Note that this does not imply that whether corrective justice or distributive justice should be implemented in any one case is an apolitical question. See Weinrib, supra note 11, at 70, 210–211. 56. ETHICS, supra note 1, at 179–186 [1131b25–1134a15]. 57. 1951 App. Cas. 850 (H.L. 1951). 58. See, e.g., HAROLD LUNTZ & DAVID HAMBLY, TORTS: CASES AND COMMENTARY 196–197 (4th ed., 1995). Aristotle on Equity, Law, and Justice 47 hence with the kind of justice appropriate in this area of the law. However, corrective justice is not all there is to justice, and hence the cricket club may have been acting equitably in not standing on its legal rights and allowing the plaintiff to retain the damages originally paid. Here, then, we may say that the defendant was right (as a matter of distributive justice) to allow the plaintiff to retain the money and the House of Lords was right (as a matter of corrective justice) to find for the defendant and hence allow the defendant (also as a matter of corrective justice) to insist on the return of that money. With respect to this area of law, then, the equitable man is the one guided by justice as a whole rather than by corrective justice alone. As there is no form of justice that stands above distributive justice and corrective justice, the equitable man must judge as to which should rule when those forms of justice come into conflict. In some cases, the equitable man will be prepared to accept less than his share according to law because he recognizes that the law enforces only a part of justice.59 D. Law and Arbitration The above also enables us to resolve our final outstanding problem: the need for arbitration. In Aristotle’s view, law is unfit to govern some areas of human life because justice with respect to those areas cannot be approximated either by general principle, and hence by legislation, or by corrective justice. These are the areas in which distributive justice is most appropriate but cannot be approximated in legislation. In these areas, judges should be replaced by arbitrators who are to rely on their sense of absolute justice. In conclusion, then, equity plays two distinct roles. In law, it enables judges to implement the intent of legislation rather than its literal meaning. Out- side law, it requires citizens to question whether their legal rights are abso- lutely just. It bears little resemblance to Equity in the common law and has nothing to do with rebellion against law. VI. PUBLIC AND PRIVATE LAW The above suggests, though it does not necessarily imply, a neat distinction between public and private law. On this view, private law is based on cor- rective justice, which is independent of distributive justice and politics, and hence could operate outside specific legislation.60 On the other hand, public 59. See also Pattantyus, supra note 35, at 215–216. This argument also applies to the law based on distributive justice. That is, sometimes the equitable man would decline to enforce in his favor a law that correctly instantiates distributive justice, because that law is inconsistent with corrective justice. This follows because there is no relationship of priority between corrective and distributive justice. See infra, text accompanying note 67. 60. ETHICS,supra note 17, at 179–186 [1131b25–1134a15]. 48 ALLAN BEEVER law would be designed to reflect the nature of the constitution and would correspond to the conception of distributive justice captured in the constitu- tion. This would rely predominantly, or perhaps exclusively, on legislation.61 As I now show, an argument for this view is at least latent in Aristotle’s theory. In the Politics, though arguing that aristocracy—the rule of the virtuous— is the ideal form of government, Aristotle also insists that it is unlikely to be realizable in practice.62 This is because aristocracy depends on the abil- ity to determine and promote to power the truly virtuous and because it supposes that there will be agreement on such. Because this is unrealistic, Aristotle settles for polity, a combination of democracy and oligarchy in which decision-making is distributed (unequally) through the citizenry. But if that is so, then it cannot be appropriate for judges to decide matters of distributive justice. Issues of distributive justice are political questions rightly to be decided by political bodies, not by aristocratic judges. In this sense, in court equity is “a mute divinity who cannot be heard.”63 On this view, then, because of its inherently political nature, distributive justice is not an appropriate subject for the courtroom unless embedded in legislation. That argument, however, would not apply to corrective justice, as that form of justice does not rest on political controversial views.64 Accordingly, the judicial enforcement of corrective justice would not amount to judicial aristocracy. VII. ARISTOTLE’S FORMALISM Whether or not the model enunciated in the previous section of this article would have been accepted by Aristotle, the distinction between the kind of law designed to reflect distributive justice and the kind of law based on corrective justice is important in assessing whether Aristotle accepted a version of legal formalism. Clearly Aristotle holds no formalist theory with respect to the creation of law based on distributive justice. Distributive justice possesses a form, but that form generates specific content only in conjunction with a conception of virtue and happiness. But there are many such conceptions, and it is the task of politics to choose between them. However, this does not justify Gardner’s claim that Aristotle rejects the notion “that law, so long as it remains true to its own distinctive form, can- not but be just.”65 This is because, on Aristotle’s view, the kind of law that relates to distributive justice (public law?) should reflect the conception of distributive justice captured in the constitution. Hence, though the form of distributive justice itself cannot generate specific content, in conjunction 61. Burns, supra note 51, at 163; Kelsen, supra note 51, at 133. 62. POLITICS, supra note 29, at bk. IV. 63. Immanuel Kant, The Metaphysics of Morals, in PRACTICAL PHILOSOPHY 353, 391 [6:234] (Mary Gregor, ed., 1996). 64. See supra, text accompanying notes 53–54. 65. Gardner, supra note 10, at 12. Aristotle on Equity, Law, and Justice 49 with a constitution it does do so. In a democratic society, the form of this area of the law will be the form of democratic distributive justice. Hence, in such a society, if the law relevant to distributive justice remains true to its form—namely, democratic distributive justice—then it cannot but be just. Certainly this does not mean that the law is absolutely just, as the democratic conception of distributive justice may be false. Nevertheless, Aristotle insists that this area of the law should reflect the constitution—“the laws are, and ought to be, framed with a view to the constitution”66—and hence even if the constitution is itself unjust, the law is just in the appropriate sense if it re- flects the constitution. In other words, for Aristotle, the appropriate (ideal) perspective from which to evaluate the justice of those laws relevant to dis- tributive justice is not absolute distributive justice but the conception of distributive justice as captured in the constitution. Accordingly, Aristotle’s position at this point is recognizably formalist. On the other hand, Aristotle holds that the appropriate perspective from which to evaluate the justice of the constitution is absolute distributive justice. Unsurprisingly, Aristotle is not a political formalist. I turn now to the area of law governed by corrective justice (private law?). The form of this law is corrective justice, and that form of justice in itself generates specific content. Now, the form of this law is not justice in total but it is a part of justice. Hence in this area too, if the law remains true to its form then it cannot but be just. But is this not a merely Pyrrhic victory? If an area of law instantiates only corrective justice or only distributive justice, then it is not coextensive with justice as a whole. It is, therefore, not really just. However, it is important to remember that distributive and corrective justice are both forms of justice. Aristotle does not argue that there is any priority between the two forms.67 It is not that distributive justice is real justice while corrective justice is only a pale approximation, or vice versa. Nor is the view that there is a higher form of justice of which corrective and distributive justice are elements. Rather, corrective justice and distributive justice are the two forms of justice. Corrective justice, then, is a part of justice, but it is not a partial justice. Hence if the law instantiates corrective justice, then it really is just—not just in all senses of the term “justice,” but nevertheless really just. Similarly, a law that accurately captures distributive justice is genuinely just, though it is unlikely to be consistent with corrective justice and hence is not just in all senses of that term. Note that it is no part of Aristotle’s view—and no part of the view of any modern legal formalist—that the positive law that exists or has existed at any point in time is necessarily just.68 Rather, the claim is that the positive law is to be judged from the perspective of a particular form of justice—corrective 66. POLITICS supra note 29, at 92 [1289a13–15]. 67. See supra note 59. 68. Weinrib, supra note 11, at 195, note 57. 50 ALLAN BEEVER justice or the conception of distributive justice found in the constitution— and hence that a form of justice can be said to underlie the positive law. There is nothing self-congratulatory about this position. It is the view that it is the task of the law—and hence the task of those whose responsibility it is to shape the positive law—to actualize corrective justice or the concep- tion of distributive justice found in the constitution. This is, of course, quite consistent with the view that the positive law in many places fails to instan- tiate these types of justice and is therefore objectionable. The position is self-congratulatory only if “law” and “the form of the law” are anachronisti- cally equated with “positive law.” The criticism, then, involves a positivistic caricature of legal formalism and distorts our understanding of Aristotle’s views. work_azregy5nf5ettkvvovcvllmxqa ---- wp-p1m-39.ebi.ac.uk Params is empty 404 sys_1000 exception wp-p1m-39.ebi.ac.uk no 221728657 Params is empty 221728657 exception Params is empty 2021/04/06-03:20:25 if (typeof jQuery === "undefined") document.write('[script type="text/javascript" src="/corehtml/pmc/jig/1.14.8/js/jig.min.js"][/script]'.replace(/\[/g,String.fromCharCode(60)).replace(/\]/g,String.fromCharCode(62))); // // // window.name="mainwindow"; .pmc-wm {background:transparent repeat-y top left;background-image:url(/corehtml/pmc/pmcgifs/wm-nobrand.png);background-size: auto, contain} .print-view{display:block} Page not available Reason: The web page address (URL) that you used may be incorrect. Message ID: 221728657 (wp-p1m-39.ebi.ac.uk) Time: 2021/04/06 03:20:25 If you need further help, please send an email to PMC. Include the information from the box above in your message. Otherwise, click on one of the following links to continue using PMC: Search the complete PMC archive. Browse the contents of a specific journal in PMC. Find a specific article by its citation (journal, date, volume, first page, author or article title). http://europepmc.org/abstract/MED/ work_b2cnsvxec5fzxnzzw5e4c2e7xy ---- PROPERTY AND TRANSITIONAL JUSTICE 65 PROPERTY AND TRANSITIONAL JUSTICE Bernadette Atuahene * Transitional justice is the study of the mechanisms employed by communities, states, and the international community to promote social reconstruction by addressing the legacy of systematic human rights abuses and authoritarianism. The transitional justice literature discussing how states can address past civil and political rights violations through truth commissions and international and domestic prosecutions is well-developed compared to the transitional justice literature concerning the redress of past property rights violations. Nevertheless, history is ripe with examples of states and private actors that have systematically and unjustly taken real property from one group and given it to another. The goal of this Article is to further an important conversation about how transitional states can address these past property rights violations to promote social reconstruction. I discuss the strengths and weaknesses of a state’s three main options: (1) maintaining the present property status quo, (2) fully or partially returning to a prior property status quo, or (3) creating a new property status quo altogether. I argue that a state should decide which option to choose through an inclusive public dialogue in which participants are well-informed rather than through a process involving only elites, which, despite being less time-consuming and less costly, would be inadequate in the long run. INTRODUCTION ........................................................................................................................ 66 I. THE HYPOTHETICAL NATION OF NAIKU ....................................................................... 69 II. OPTIONS AVAILABLE TO THE NATION OF NAIKU ......................................................... 73 A. Option One: Maintaining the Present Property Status Quo ............................... 73 B. Option Two: Fully or Partially Returning to a Prior Property Status Quo ......... 74 1. Return to T1 or T2 .......................................................................................... 81 2. Return to T3 .................................................................................................... 83 C. Option Three: Creating a New Property Status Quo ........................................... 84 1. Tax and Transfer ............................................................................................. 84 2. Land Redistribution......................................................................................... 86 * Assistant Professor, Chicago-Kent College of Law, and Faculty Fellow, American Bar Foundation. J.D. 2002, Yale Law School; M.P.A. 2002, Harvard University, John F. Kennedy School of Government; B.A. 1997, University of California, Los Angeles. I would like to thank Cathy Baker, Charlton Copeland, Ewurama Ewusi-Mensah, Sarah Harding, and Carlton Waterhouse, as well as my colleagues who offered valuable feedback when I presented this Article at the Chicago-Kent Faculty Workshop, the 2010 Law and Society Annual Conference, and the Workshop on the Role of Law in Developing Transition Countries at University of Wisconsin, Madison. Stephanie Crawford, Geetu Naik, Matthew Savin, and Shannon Smith provided exceptional research and library assistance, for which I am very grateful. 66 58 UCLA LAW REVIEW DISCOURSE 65 (2010) III. THE PROCESS OF CHOOSING FROM THE AVAILABLE OPTIONS .................................... 89 CONCLUSION............................................................................................................................ 93 INTRODUCTION History is rife with examples of state and private actors systematically confiscating property from one group without consent and without paying just compensation and then transferring that property to another group. I call these actions property dispossession or property theft.1 In some cases, dispos- sessed populations have made resounding cries for reparations during the transitions from the offending regimes to the new political orders.2 During Communism, for example, several Eastern European governments took property from the aristocracy and Nazi sympathizers to distribute it to their peasant popu- lations.3 After the fall of these governments, pre-Communist owners in the Czech Republic, Estonia, Germany, Hungary, Latvia, Lithuania, and Slovakia demanded reparations.4 To placate these constituencies, the transitional gov- ernments had to determine how to address the property dispossession that had occurred during Communism.5 1. It is a violation of human rights to confiscate property without consent and compensation. See Universal Declaration of Human Rights, G.A. Res. 217A, at 74, U.N. GAOR, 3d Sess., 1st plen. mtg., U.N. Doc. A/810 (Dec. 12, 1948) (“No one shall be arbitrarily deprived of his property.”). 2. See infra notes 3–12 and accompanying text for several examples. See also Mark Everingham, Agricultural Property Rights and Political Change in Nicaragua, 43 LATIN AM. POL. & SOC’Y 61 (2001); George Meszaros, Taking the Land Into Their Hands: The Landless Workers’ Movement and the Brazilian State, 27 J.L. & SOC’Y 517 (2000) (describing how the Landless Workers’ Movement used direct action techniques to demand implementation of land reform policies in Brazil). 3. See Rainer Frank, Privatization in Eastern Germany: A Comprehensive Study, 27 VAND. J. TRANSNAT’L L. 809, 812–13 (1994) (noting that from 1945 to 1949, the Soviet Military Administration of Germany confiscated all property holdings that exceeded 250 acres and initiated land reform to benefit “the general good of the working class”); see also Richard W. Crowder, Comment, Restitution in the Czech Republic: Problems and Prague-Nosis, 5 IND. INT’L. & COMP. L. REV. 237, 238 (1994) (noting that from 1945 to 1948, the Czechoslovak government confiscated the land belonging to those “who had collaborated or sympathized with the Nazis during the Second World War”). 4. See Nicolás J. Gutiérrez, Jr., Righting Old Wrongs: A Survey of Restitution Schemes for Possible Application to a Democratic Cuba, 4 U. MIAMI Y.B. INT’L L. 111 (1995) (reviewing restitution programs in the Baltic Republics, Bulgaria, Czech Republic, East Germany, Hungary, Nicaragua, Poland, Romania, and Slovakia); Mariana Karadjova, Property Restitution in Eastern Europe: Domestic and International Human Rights Law Responses, 29 REV. CENT. & E. EUR. L. 325 (2004) (presenting an overview of Eastern European restitution programs). 5. Not all post-Communist countries opted to return to a prior property status quo. See Frances H. Foster, Restitution of Expropriated Property: Post-Soviet Lessons for Cuba, 34 COLUM. J. TRANSNAT’L L. 621, 625–26 (1996) (noting that Russian land reform laws have “prohibited the ‘return of land plots to former owners and their heirs’” and that Tajikistan has enacted similar laws). Property and Transitional Justice 67 Similarly, beginning in 1652, Europeans arrived in southern Africa, estab- lished economic and political dominance, and brutally took ownership of vast swaths of land from the African majority.6 In the 1980s and 1990s, Zimbabwe, South Africa, and Namibia transitioned from white minority rule to majority rule.7 One of the greatest challenges faced by these new African governments was how to help the African population reclaim their stolen land.8 Similar events have taken place in the Middle East. Saddam Hussein’s rise to power culminated in 1979 when he was named president of Iraq. Over the course of his dictatorship, he subjected Kurds to severe discrimination— including unjust confiscation of their property.9 In 2003, American troops ousted Hussein, setting the groundwork for Iraq’s tumultuous political transi- tion in which the Kurds gained significant political power.10 For the Kurds, addressing past property dispossession was a political priority, but choosing the manner in which to proceed proved challenging. Another example of property dispossession is the Rwandan genocide of 1994, in which significant amounts of property were stolen or unwillingly aban- doned by citizens fleeing ethnic violence. In fact, one impetus behind the mass killings was the desire of many Hutus to confiscate Tutsi property.11 When the 6. Alois Mlambo, The Ambiguities of Independence, Zimbabwe 1980–1990, in UNFINISHED BUSINESS: THE LAND CRISIS IN SOUTHERN AFRICA 57, 64 (Margaret C. Lee & Karen Colvard eds., 2003). 7. Id. at 57, 65; Justine Hunter, Introduction to WHO SHOULD OWN THE LAND? ANALYSES AND VIEWS ON LAND REFORM AND THE LAND QUESTION IN NAMIBIA AND SOUTHERN AFRICA 1–6 (Justine Hunter ed., 2004); Cherryl Walker, The Limits to Land Reform: Rethinking “The Land Question”, 31 J. S. AFR. STUD. 805, 805–24 (2005). 8. See Mlambo, supra note 6, at 87, 411. 9. See JOHN FAWCETT & VICTOR TANNER, THE BROOKINGS INSTITUTION—SAIS PROJECT ON INTERNAL DISPLACEMENT, THE INTERNALLY DISPLACED PEOPLE OF IRAQ 10 (2002), available at http://www.brookings.edu/~/media/Files/rc/papers/2002/10iraq_fawcett/iraqreport.pdf (explaining that the al-Anfal operation, which began in 1988, was based on the message that “the regime and its soldiers had a nigh-religious right to take Kurdish property and lives”). 10. See QUIL LAWRENCE, INVISIBLE NATION: HOW THE KURDS’ QUEST FOR STATEHOOD IS SHAPING IRAQ AND THE MIDDLE EAST 235–36 (2008); Edward Wong, Back From Exile, Kurds Demand Political Power and Reparations for Seized Property, N.Y. TIMES, Jan. 19, 2004, at A9 (noting that the Kurds, recently back from exile, strongly demanded political rights and reparations from the transi- tional government). 11. See MAHMOOD MAMDANI, WHEN VICTIMS BECOME KILLERS: COLONIALISM, NATIVISM, AND THE GENOCIDE IN RWANDA 193 (2001) (noting that a pattern emerged in which “[p]refects and burgomasters organized Hutu militants who identified and targeted Tutsi ‘collaborators,’ took over the land of those who were killed or fled, and redistributed it to militants”); GÉRARD PRUNIER, THE RWANDA CRISIS 1959–1994: HISTORY OF A GENOCIDE 248 (1995) (noting that while the desire to acquire Tutsi land was not the primary motivation behind the 1994 mass killings, there was “an element of material interest in the killings . . . . Villagers also probably had a vague hope that if things settled down after the massacres they could obtain pieces of land belonging to the victims, a strong lure in such a land- starved country as Rwanda”); Mark A. Drumbl, Punishment, Postgenocide: From Guilt to Shame to Civis 68 58 UCLA LAW REVIEW DISCOURSE 65 (2010) genocidal killing abated, Paul Kagame seized the reins of power and began the political transition. President Kagame—like many other leaders in times of transition—was forced to ask the recurrent transitional justice question: What can our government do about past property dispossession?12 Transitional justice is the study of those mechanisms employed by communities, states, and the international community to promote social reconstruction by addressing the legacy of systematic human rights abuses and authoritarianism. There is a well-developed transitional justice literature discussing how states can deal with past violations of civil and political rights such as incarceration, murder, sexual abuse, and torture.13 There has also been healthy discussion about the value of truth commissions and international and domestic prosecutions concerning these violations.14 Despite the important experiences of nations in Eastern Europe and Southern Africa, Iraq, and Rwanda that I have discussed, the transitional justice literature on how to address past property rights violations is significantly less developed.15 in Rwanda, 75 N.Y.U. L. REV. 1221, 1249–250 (2000) (noting that some Hutu “pillaged, stole, ransacked, and appropriated property from homes in which Tutsi had been killed or from which they had fled”). 12. PRUNIER, supra note 11, at 332 (noting that post-genocide, the Rwandan government struggled with “property grabbing by the former refugees now coming back from Uganda and Burundi”). 13. See, e.g., 1 TRANSITIONAL JUSTICE: HOW EMERGING DEMOCRACIES RECKON WITH FORMER REGIMES (Neil J. Kritz ed., 1995); Kuk Cho, Transitional Justice in Korea: Legally Coping With Past Wrongs After Democratization, 16 PAC. RIM L. & POL’Y J. 579 (2007); Omar Encarnación, Reconciliation After Democratization: Coping With the Past in Spain, 123 POL. SCI. Q. 435 (2008); Saira Mohamed, A Neglected Option: The Contributions of State Responsibility for Genocide to Transitional Justice, 80 U. COLO. L. REV. 329 (2009); Binaifer Nowrojee, Making the Invisible War Crime Visible: Post-Conflict Justice for Sierra Leone’s Rape Victims, 18 HARV. HUM. RTS. J. 85 (2005); Chandra Lekha Sriram, Revolutions in Accountability: New Approaches to Past Abuses, 19 AM. U. INT’L L. REV. 301 (2003). 14. See CHARLES VILLA-VICENCIO & WILHELM VERWOERD, LOOKING BACK REACHING FORWARD: REFLECTIONS ON THE TRUTH AND RECONCILIATION COMMISSION OF SOUTH AFRICA (2000); RICHARD A. WILSON, THE POLITICS OF TRUTH AND RECONCILIATION IN SOUTH AFRICA: LEGITIMIZING THE POST-APARTHEID STATE (2001); Daniel J. Hendy, Is a Truth Commission the Solution to Restoring Peace in Post-Conflict Iraq?, 20 OHIO ST. J. ON DISP. RESOL. 527 (2005); Richard John Galvin, The Case for a Japanese Truth Commission Covering World War II Era Japanese War Crimes, 11 TUL. J. INT’L & COMP. L. 59 (2003); Stephan Landsman, Alternative Responses to Serious Human Rights Abuses: Of Prosecution and Truth Commissions, 59 LAW & CONTEMP. PROBS. 81 (1996); Margaret Popkin, The Salvadoran Truth Commission and the Search for Justice, 15 CRIM. L.F. 105 (2004); Michael P. Scharf, The Case for a Permanent International Truth Commission, 7 DUKE J. COMP. & INT’L L. 375 (1997); Peter A. Schey, Dinah L. Shelton & Naomi Roht-Arriaza, Addressing Human Rights Abuses: Truth Commissions and the Value of Amnesty, 19 WHITTIER L. REV. 325 (1997); Carsten Stahn, Accommodating Individual Criminal Responsibility and National Reconciliation: The UN Truth Commission for East Timor, 95 AM. J. INT’L L. 952 (2001). 15. For a few examples of transitional justice literature about past property rights viola- tions, see RETURNING HOME: HOUSING AND PROPERTY RESTITUTION RIGHTS OF REFUGEES AND DISPLACED PERSONS 3 (Scott Leckie ed., 2003); Bernadette Atuahene, From Reparation to Restoration: Moving Beyond Restoring Property Rights to Restoring Political and Economic Visibility, 60 SMU L. REV. 1419 (2007) [hereinafter Atuahene, From Reparation to Restoration]; Bernadette Atuahene, Property Rights and the Demands of Transformation, 31 MICH. J. INT’L. L. 765 (2010); Bernadette Atuahene, Things Property and Transitional Justice 69 In this Article, I explore the effects of past property theft on the current property status quo. The property status quo or property distribution is the existing distribution of property among various racial, ethnic, or religious groups in a society. This status quo is important because property ownership structures group relations. When one group owns a disproportionate amount of property, the resulting asymmetries in social status and economic power can leave weaker groups open to various forms of subordination, which can foster deep resentment that undermines social reconstruction.16 When transitional states have the political will to address past property theft and promote social reconstruction, the enduring question is: How can a transitional state accomplish these goals? The answer to the question is complex and highly contextual. Thus, in Part I, to isolate the key issues that many countries face, I discuss a hypothetical transitional state called Naiku with a historical record that accentuates the challenges at hand. In Part II, I discuss Naiku’s three main options: (1) maintaining the present property status quo, (2) fully or partially returning to a prior property status quo, or (3) creating a new property status quo. In Part III, I argue that when a transitional state is determining the most advantageous option, its decisionmaking process is cru- cial. A state should decide which option to pursue through an inclusive public dialogue with well-informed participants rather than through a less time- consuming, less costly process involving only elites. I. THE HYPOTHETICAL NATION OF NAIKU I have created the hypothetical African state of Naiku to illustrate my argument regarding the redress of past property theft. Three events in Naiku’s history radically transformed the country’s property allocation, and each one led to a new property status quo. The country is now on the cusp of its fourth potentially transformative event. Fall Apart: The Illegitimacy of Property Rights in the Context of Past Property Theft, 51 ARIZ. L. REV. 829 (2009) [hereinafter Atuahene, Things Fall Apart]; Scott Leckie, Housing and Property Issues for Refugees and Internally Displaced Persons in the Context of Return: Key Considerations for UNHCR Policy and Practice, REFUGEE SURV. Q., Iss. 3, 2000, at 5. 16. See Daron Acemoglu & James A. Robinson, A Theory of Political Transitions, 91 AM. ECON. REV. 938, 957 (2001) (finding that high levels of inequality between groups in society lead to political instability); Ruth Hall, A Political Economy of Land Reform in South Africa, 31 REV. AFR. POL. ECON. 213, 214 (2004) (noting the World Bank’s contention that redistributing the land in South Africa was necessary to avert social and political instability); Jaime Crook, Comment, Promoting Peace and Economic Security in Rwanda Through Fair and Equitable Land Rights, 94 CAL. L. REV. 1487, 1490 (2006) (arguing that the Rwandan government must further promote equitable land access through land reform to promote peace and stability). 70 58 UCLA LAW REVIEW DISCOURSE 65 (2010) I. Archeologists have confirmed that the people of the small kingdom of Alim were the first modern humans to occupy the region now known as the country of Naiku. The Alim were farmers who tilled the fertile land. No one owned land, but custom dictated that all had rights to use it according to their needs. Following a sudden boom in the popula- tion of the neighboring nation of Alieu, coupled with a severe drought, the people of Alieu ventured out of their occupied territory in 1810 and conquered the Naiku region, bringing the concept of communal land ownership with them. The Alieu murdered the Alim leadership but incor- porated the Alim people into the Alieu nation as full citizens with equal rights. Under the Alieu property system, the chief formally owned and controlled all land and gave members of the nation use rights according to each family’s needs. In the new Alieu nation, the people of Alim and Alieu lived side-by-side peacefully and intermarried often. II. One hundred years later in 1910, the British arrived, vanquished the nation of Alieu, declared Naiku a colony, and claimed sovereignty over Naiku’s land. They immediately evicted the natives from 90 percent of the land, divided that land into deeded lots, transferred the lots to British settlers and several members of the Alieu nation who cooperated with the British government, and created a land registry to maintain a record of ownership.17 The British settlers were economically and politically dominant from this point on. III. In 1996, the warriors of Alieu united under the leadership of General Abdeena, ousted the British, and won independence for their people. Ab- deena was initially highly respected and hailed as the country’s redeemer, but quickly became unpopular because she ruled with a heavy hand and failed to redistribute land as promised. Instead, without paying just com- pensation and without consent, she expropriated all the deeded lots 17. This situation is similar to that in southern Africa. See Johan van Tooyen & Bongiwe Njobe- Mbuli, Access to Land: Selecting the Beneficiaries, in AGRICULTURAL LAND REFORM IN SOUTH AFRICA: POLICIES, MARKETS AND MECHANISMS 461 (van Zyl et al. eds., 1996) (“Land distribution in South Africa is highly skewed. Approximately 87 percent of agricultural land is held by almost 67,000 white farmers and accommodates a total population of 5.3 million. The remaining 71 percent of the popula- tion, which is predominantly black, live on 13 percent of the land in high density areas—the former homelands.”). The same is true in Namibia and was true in Zimbabwe prior to its tumultuous land reform program in 2002. See Uazuva Kaumbi, Namibia: The Land is Ours!, NEW AFR. Feb. 2004, at 28 (“[L]ess than 10% of the people own more than 80% of the commercial farmland as a result of colonial theft.”); J.S. Juana, A Quantitative Analysis of Zimbabwe’s Land Reform Policy: An Application of Zimbabwe SAM Multipliers, 45 AGREKON 294, 294 (2006) (“During the colonial era, land was distributed on racial lines, with approximately 4,660 large-scale predominantly white commercial farmers owning about 14.8 million hectares and about 6 million black smallholder farmers owning about 16.4 million hectares in mainly low agricultural potential areas.”). Property and Transitional Justice 71 distributed by the British in years prior and transferred over 65 percent of these lots to herself, her family, and her political cronies.18 IV. In 2009, Abdeena was deposed in a bloodless coup, and soon thereafter a new government took power in Naiku’s first democratic election. Layla was elected president, in large part, based on her promise to transform the property distribution. This political transition placed Naiku on the cusp of the fourth event with the potential to drastically transform its property status quo. Most citizens—both black and white—agreed that the present property distribution was unjust because General Abdeena’s corrupt allo- cations of property were patently unfair. But, the corrupt transfers of land made by the general were complicated by the fact that, by 2009, the owners had sold 20 percent of the deeded lots to innocent third parties at market prices. CHRONOLOGY OF LAND OWNERSHIP T1 (pre-1810) T2 (1810) T3 (1910) T4 (1996) T5 (2009) Alim Alim & Alieu British settlers Independence under General Abdeena Democracy under Layla 1st transformation 2nd transformation 3rd transformation 4th transformation? The vast majority of Naiku’s citizens agree that the state must do something about the multiple layers of land dispossession, so there is tre- mendous political will to transform present property arrangements. Today the population of Naiku is as follows: The Alim and Alieu (who are black) constitute about 80 percent of the population, while the offspring of British settlers (who are white) constitute about 10 percent. An additional 10 percent of the population falls under the category of “other” by either claiming both British and African ancestry or some other ancestry altogether. The economi- cally dominant descendants of the British settlers, backed by the British government, are demanding a return to T3—the property distribution that was 18. General Abdeena’s controversial redistribution of property is similar to what happened in Zimbabwe as a result of its fast-track program. See CRAIG RICHARDSON, THE COLLAPSE OF ZIMBABWE IN THE WAKE OF THE 2000–2003 LAND REFORMS (2004); Neil H. Thomas, Land Reform in Zimbabwe, 24 THIRD WORLD Q. 691, 700–02 (2003); INTERNATIONAL MONETARY FUND COUNTRY REPORT NO. 05/359, ZIMBABWE: SELECTED ISSUES AND STATISTICAL APPENDIX 13 (2005) (noting that the lack of transparency has made it difficult to determine who benefited from the land reform by presently residing on confiscated farms). 72 58 UCLA LAW REVIEW DISCOURSE 65 (2010) in place just before independence in 1996.19 Meanwhile, the people of Alim and Alieu—now politically powerful—are demanding a return to T2, the pre- colonial property distribution, or to start anew. A small faction, which traces its ancestry directly back to the Alim, is demanding a return to T1 when the Alim people were the sole inhabitants of Naiku. In the midst of these varied demands and stark uncertainty, one thing is definite: To consolidate the politi- cal transition, Layla’s government must create an efficient yet fair resolution to the multiple layers of land dispossession that have occurred in Naiku. T5 is a crossroads for Naiku because the nation has the opportunity to rec- oncile its past in order to secure its future. There are some constraints, however. A government’s freedom to imagine alternatives is bound by the extant but unwritten rules that transitional states (especially resource-deprived transitional states) must follow to gain acceptance into the new globalized economy. If transitional states do not comply with these rules, they will likely experience a decrease in the bilateral, multilateral, and private sector funding necessary for economic development.20 At least one nonnegotiable rule for acceptance in the globalized economy is the commitment to protecting private property rights and promoting free-market democracy. Naiku’s newly elected government is aware of this requirement but remains determined to create a property distri- bution that the vast majority of its citizens view as legitimate. There are, however, problems with each of Naiku’s past property status quos. General Abdeena’s 1996 land transfers to herself, her family, and her political cronies at T4 was unquestionably unjust; given the short span of time that has passed since then, this injustice still dominates the society’s collective memory. The violent British acquisition of Naiku and the transfer of deeded plots to British settlers and their supporters at T3 were equally illegitimate. Although these events occurred a century ago, the resulting unequal, racially skewed property distribution lasted until 1996 and has been the source of much anger and outrage among the African majority. Consequently, the injustice is fresh in the nation’s collective memory and has proven to be an explosive issue in current Naiku politics. The kingdom of Alim’s defeat, the massacre of its leaders, and expropriation of its land at T2 were similarly unjust. As a result of the lapse of time between the present and T2 (about two hundred years), 19. See, e.g., Cheryl Harris, Whiteness as Property, 106 HARV. L. REV. 1710, 1730 (1993) (arguing that in societies structured around principles of white superiority and racial subordination, white privilege can become a quintessential expectation of that society). 20. See Tony Killick, Conditionality and IMF Flexibility, in THE IMF, WORLD BANK AND POLICY REFORM 253 (Alberto Paloni & Maurizio Zanardi eds., 2006) (noting that the International Monetary Fund imposes conditions to ensure that member states use funds for policies that are consistent with the IMF’s objectives). Property and Transitional Justice 73 these are the only events of dispossession that play a nominal role in the nation’s collective memory and are not politically divisive. Given the complicated history of dispossession and its effects on the present state of affairs, Naiku must carefully decide its path at T5. II. OPTIONS AVAILABLE TO THE NATION OF NAIKU The state’s role in determining ownership patterns is especially pronounced in nations like Naiku where there have been multiple layers of property dispos- session that have created multiple potentially legitimate claims to the same plots of land. In transitional states, the government’s decision to address or ignore past property theft determines who will be considered the legitimate owner of each plot. Naiku’s government has three possible courses of action at T5: (1) maintaining the present property status quo, (2) fully or partially returning to a prior property status quo, or (3) creating a new property status quo altogether. A. Option One: Maintaining the Present Property Status Quo If Layla’s government chooses to maintain the present property status quo, it will look forward and not address the multiple layers of past land dispos- session in Naiku. Instead, her government will rely on the market to place resources in the hands of those who will use them most efficiently. From an efficiency standpoint, who initially owns the property is irrelevant because the properties will end up in the hands of those who value them most highly, if transaction costs are low.21 Thus, following the examples of Namibia, South Africa, and Zimbabwe in their transitions to democracy, Naiku can allow current trade and investment to continue unencumbered by giving current landowners clear title to their property despite how it was acquired.22 Maintaining the present property status quo ensures that investment and trade are not attenuated by protecting existing investment-backed expec- tations, including the expectation that innocent third parties who bought property during T4 at market rates will retain rights to that property without fear of expropriation. This option also requires the least bureaucratic interven- tion, consequently making it the least vulnerable to government failure, which “arises when government has created inefficiencies because it should not have 21. See RICHARD A. POSNER, FRONTIERS OF LEGAL THEORY 6 (2001) (“The ‘Coase Theorem’ holds that where market transaction costs are zero, the law’s initial assignment of rights is irrelevant to efficiency, since if the assignment is inefficient the parties will rectify it by a corrective transaction.”). 22. A.J. Van Der Walt, The Constitutional Property Clause: Striking a Balance Between Guarantee and Limitation, in PROPERTY AND THE CONSTITUTION 109, 111–12 (Janet McLean ed., 1999). 74 58 UCLA LAW REVIEW DISCOURSE 65 (2010) intervened in the first place or when it could have solved a given problem or set of problems more efficiently.”23 One central flaw is that maintaining the present status quo legally legitimizes a patently unfair land distribution. Before General Abdeena was deposed, she titled a vast amount of land to herself, her family, and her political cronies; consequently, the vast majority of citizens view present-day ownership patterns as illegitimate. Most importantly, this commonly held view of the cur- rent property distribution has engendered a great amount of societal resentment and anger. Layla’s government must ensure that this discontent is channeled in an orderly manner through existing social, legal, and political institutions; oth- erwise, the country risks economic-based political turmoil.24 Even if maintaining the current status quo is the most economically efficient option, Layla’s gov- ernment should choose a different option to avoid economic-based political turmoil.25 B. Option Two: Fully or Partially Returning to a Prior Property Status Quo The second option Naiku has at T5 is to fully or partially return to a prior property status quo by taking the present property distribution as a starting point and using its powers of eminent domain to make land available for return to past owners.26 If significant time has passed, and the state can no longer identify the beneficiaries of past unjust transfers, then it must provide the funds to purchase property from its general coffers. If, however, the beneficiaries of past unjust transfers are readily identifiable, the state can require them to fully or partially finance the return of property.27 23. CLIFFORD WINSTON, GOVERNMENT FAILURE VERSUS MARKET FAILURE: MICROECONOMICS POLICY RESEARCH AND GOVERNMENT PERFORMANCE 2–3 (2006). 24. For a detailed discussion of disobedience resulting from past property theft, see Atuahene, Things Fall Apart, supra note 15. 25. See Mark J. Roe, Essay, Backlash, 98 COLUM. L. REV. 217, 217 (1998) (“Voters may see market arrangements as unfair, leading them to lash back and disrupt otherwise efficient arrangements. To quell this backlash, inefficient legal structures may arise and survive, despite the fact that they could not withstand a normal efficiency critique. The prospect of backlash—or of strategically tempering otherwise efficient rules and institutions to finesse away a more destructive backlash—complicates a law and economics inquiry.”). 26. This is the decision that the South African transitional government made. See Matthew Chaskalson, Stumbling Towards Section 28: Negotiations Over the Protection of Property Rights in the Interim Constitution, 11 S. AFR. J. HUM. RTS. 222, 229–38 (1995) (providing an insider’s view of the pre-liberation negotiation that led to the constitutional property clause, which protected existing property rights). 27. This is what happened in the Netherlands after World War II. See Wouter Veraart, ‘Reasonableness’ or Strict Law? The Postwar Restitution of Property Rights in the Netherlands and in France (1945–1952), in YAD VASHEM—THE INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE ON CONFRONTING HISTORY: THE HISTORICAL COMMISSIONS OF INQUIRY (2002) (on file with UCLA Law Review) (noting that the strict restitution law in France made it easier for former owners of property to get their land Property and Transitional Justice 75 To implement this option, Naiku can use two types of redistributive programs: reparations or restoration. Reparations programs are designed to vindicate past property rights.28 In a reparations program, if property was confis- cated unjustly, then the dispossessed have a window of time to file claims. These claims are vetted through a judicial or administrative process to determine whether compensation is warranted. A defining feature of reparations programs is that the beneficiaries do not have a great deal of choice in what they receive; they usually receive either land restitution or money as compensation. Restoration is also a specific type of redistributive program designed to vindicate a past property right.29 As with reparations, the state determines the process for accepting, validating, and paying restoration claims, but resto- ration is distinct from reparations on two counts. The first point of distinction concerns who is eligible to become a beneficiary. In a restoration program, beneficiaries must be subject to property-induced invisibility in order to qualify. As I have previously argued,30 in certain situations, dispossession involves more than the confiscation of property; it involves the removal of an individual or community from the social contract. I call this property-induced invisibility and use the work of John Locke, Carole Pateman, and Charles Mills to provide a clear definition.31 Property-induced invisibility is defined as: the widespread or systematic confiscation or destruction of real property with no payment of just compensation executed such that dehumani- zation occurs; the act is perpetrated by the state or other prevailing power structure(s), and adversely affects powerless people or people made powerless by the act such that they are effectively left economically vulnerable and dependent on the state to satisfy their basic needs. 32 For example, if a colonial government impoverished my father by confiscating his property during T3 and subjected him to property-induced invisibility, he would qualify for compensation. But, if my father has passed away and my siblings and I have become well-off, then we would not qualify for compensation back because the judge was obliged to acknowledge the nullity of any transaction of property performed after the original owner had lost his right to dispose of it, meaning that all the transactions performed by so- called administrators were null and void and had to be undone). Southern Africa does not have this luxury because the identity of wrongdoers is not as clear as it was in the Netherlands due to the passage of time between the wrongful act and rectification. 28. See generally Emma Coleman Jordan, The Non-Monetary Value of Reparations Rhetoric, 6 AFR.- AM. L. & POL’Y REP. 21 (2004) (discussing the importance of reparations for black Americans and potential challenges to reparations). 29. See Atuahene, From Reparation to Restoration, supra note 15. 30. Id. 31. Id. 32. Id. 76 58 UCLA LAW REVIEW DISCOURSE 65 (2010) from the state because we do not meet the last condition of restoration: We are not economically vulnerable and dependent on the state to meet our basic needs. In contrast, under the reparations paradigm, the current financial position of the dispossessed person or her descendants is irrelevant, so my siblings and I would qualify for compensation despite our elevated socioeconomic standing. The second point of distinction between reparations and restoration programs is what the beneficiaries receive. When the confiscation of a commu- nity’s or individual’s property causes property-induced invisibility, the state’s objective should not be simply to compensate them for the stolen property; the need is more profound. The state’s objectives should be to bring them into the social contract, to restore their visibility, and to affirm their humanity. A state can accomplish these objectives by giving the dispossessed a choice.33 It is important to allow those subject to property-induced invisibility to partici- pate in determining their compensation in order to give them control over the terms of their reentry into the body politic and affirm their humanity. The choices may include: the return of the confiscated property; the grant of alternative property if the original property is no longer available; financial compensation; or a variety of in-kind benefits, such as subsidized credit, free higher education or vocational training for two generations, or urban housing rights. 34 In contrast, the focal point of a reparations program is not providing the victim with a choice. Regardless of whether a state implements a reparations or a restoration program, to return to a prior property status quo, it must surmount six potential roadblocks. The first hurdle involves identification of program beneficiaries. When those who were originally dispossessed have died, it can be difficult to identify who should receive compensation in their stead. Some may argue that once the dispossessed person dies, his or her claims die as well. Others argue that a debt is not extinguished upon death. Instead, the debt is owed to the deceased’s estate; and so should be the case with debts arising from dispossession. If individuals of Alim and Alieu descent successfully prove that their ancestors were dispossessed during T3, then the heirs of the dispossessed should receive compensation. But, identifying heirs can be extraordinarily diffi- cult when a significant amount of time has passed between the event of 33. Id. at 1447–50 & n.102. 34. Unrestricted cash grants will not necessarily be the best form of compensation in the group context. See, e.g., Mari J. Matsuda, Looking to the Bottom: Critical Legal Studies and Reparations, 22 HARV. C.R.-C.L. L. REV. 323, 391 (1987) (noting that appropriate reparations might include “[m]oney for education, housing, medical care, food, job training, cultural preservation, recreation and other pressing needs of victim communities [that] will raise the standard of living of victim groups, promoting their survival and participation”). Property and Transitional Justice 77 dispossession and the moment of compensation. With each generation, the number of heirs increases exponentially, and the state will require complicated family trees to identify them. If the Alim and Alieu community is intact, however, it can make a community claim for compensation.35 This approach is more akin to a living victim making a claim because the community transcends the lives of its indi- vidual members and endures through time. The compensation would go to the collective for the betterment of all its members.36 All people of African descent whose ancestors were born in Naiku are part of the Alieu nation that existed at T2. Due to frequent intermarriage, a return to T1 (when the Alim were the sole occupants of the land) would be almost impossible because the Alim are no longer a distinct community. The second challenge to implementing a reparations or restoration program is obtaining verifiable proof of prior ownership or occupation. Produc- ing a deed or other official written document would be the simplest way to prove ownership or occupation, but there were no deeds in Naiku until the advent of the Europeans at T3. Nevertheless, if the nation of Naiku desires to restore rights in existence prior to T3, it can accept diverse forms of evi- dence to prove that an individual or community had a right to a particular plot of land, as South Africa did in its land restitution program.37 South Africa relied upon a variety of forms of evidence, including documents in the national archives, physical evidence such as graves or ruins that indicated occupation, and oral evidence such as testimony concerning ownership or occupation from the claimant verified against testimony from other occupants or their descen- dants who lived nearby.38 But, despite a state’s willingness to use diverse forms of evidence, the undeniable reality is that verifying who owned or occupied 35. Mark Everingham & Crystal Jannecke, Land Restitution and Democratic Citizenship in South Africa, 32 J. S. AFR. STUD. 545, 548 (2006) (describing the political role of claimant communities in South Africa); Lewis P. Hinchman & Sandra K. Hinchman, Australia’s Judicial Revolution: Aboriginal Land Rights and the Transformation of Liberalism, 31 POLITY 23, 23–51 (1998) (describing the progressive acceptance of aboriginal land claims on behalf of a community). Adrien K. Wing, Communitarianism v. Individualism: Constitutionalism in Namibia and South Africa, 11 WIS. INT’L L.J. 295, 299 (1993) (emphasizing the importance of communitarianism in both South Africa and Namibia). 36. The extensive litigation involving the U.S. cigarette industry is a testament to the fact that uncertainty over the exact identity of victims and their heirs is not an insurmountable barrier. Courts used “[s]tatistical, pro rata distribution of damages” to cure “the problem of indeterminate defendants and indeterminate [victims].” Kaimipono David Wenger, Causation and Attenuation in the Slavery Reparations Debate, 40 U.S.F. L. REV. 279, 313 (2006). 37. Interview With Daniel Jacobs, Assistant Dir., Comm’n on the Restitution of Land Rights (Mar. 15, 2008). 38. Id. 78 58 UCLA LAW REVIEW DISCOURSE 65 (2010) land becomes more difficult as time passes because, for instance, people who can provide oral evidence to confirm ownership eventually die. The third hurdle in fully or partially returning to a prior status quo is acknowledging people who never owned anything in the past. Before the state makes a decision to reinstitute a prior property status quo, there must be a national consensus that the previous arrangement was significantly more legitimate than the present one. This consensus will be informed by a nation’s memory of the past as kept alive through historical texts, oral traditions, and popular culture. Nevertheless, even if there is a consensus, the prior status quo had various imperfections and those imperfections will be restored. Con- sequently, restoring a past property status quo can serve to resurrect a former aristocracy and to exclude those who never owned property in the past. Option three, which I discuss in the following Subpart, addresses this concern directly through a full-scale redistribution of wealth. In the alternative, to address the needs of people who are currently poor and have never owned property in the past, a state can implement a restoration or reparations program in concert with significant redistribution effected through the tax and transfer system, as demonstrated in South Africa.39 The fourth challenge to returning to a prior property status quo is the uncertainty that results from using eminent domain. When returning property to prior owners, the state should use eminent domain and pay existing owners just compensation. The determination of just compensation should use the fair market value as the starting point but must also take into consideration factors such as the conditions of acquisition, acquisition price, and any state subsi- dies from which the owner benefited.40 Using eminent domain to restructure 39. STEPHEN GELB, EDGE INST., INEQUALITY IN SOUTH AFRICA: NATURE, CAUSES AND RESPONSES 55 (2003), available at http://www.sarpn.org/documents/d0000671/P686-Gelb_Inequality _in_SA.pdf (describing South Africa’s social service spending). 40. The fifth hurdle in fully or partially returning to a prior property status quo or creating a new property status quo altogether is this involves government-led redistributive efforts that are highly suscepti- ble to government corruption, inefficiency and ineptitude. See supra note 23 and accompanying text. As it stands, transitional states characteristically have weak administrative institutions that are particularly sus- ceptible to corruption, bureaucratic inefficiency, and lack of transparency. The South African Constitution provides that “the amount of compensation and the time and manner of payment must be just and equitable, reflecting an equitable balance between the public interest and the interests of those affected, having regard to all relevant circumstances, including: (a) the current use of the property; (b) the history of the acquisition and use of the property; (c) the market value of the property; (d) the extent of direct state investment and subsidy in the acquisition and beneficial capital improvement of the property; and (e) the purpose of the expropriation.” S. AFR. CONST. 1996 § 25; see also Ex Parte Former Highland Residents; In Re Ash and Others v. Dep’t of Land Affairs 2000 (2) All SA 26 (LCC) (S. Afr.) (stating that for determining just and equitable compensation, equitable balance required by the constitution will in most cases be best achieved by first determining the market value of the property and then subtracting from or adding to the amount of the market value, as other relevant circumstances may require). Property and Transitional Justice 79 property rights promotes fairness to all groups, including nonindigenous people who immigrated to Naiku in the last one hundred years and at no point bene- fited from any unjust past land transfers. The downside of using eminent domain is that it can cause uncertainty and dampen investment. Jahangir Saleh notes that “[u]ncertainty of expropriation affects the uncertainty of returns and tends to discourage investment for risk-averse decision makers.”41 This uncer- tainty begins when the redistributive program is announced (or when the public believes that it has a high probability of being implemented) and ends when the new owners of the land are determined.42 Once the uncertainty ends, trade and investment are no longer affected unless the government does not make a credible promise that the transformation is a one-time ordeal.43 The sixth and most formidable hurdle in returning to a prior property status quo is answering the question: How far back? That is, a reparations or restoration program rectifies property rights violations that occurred during a specific time period, and the state must determine the eligible time period. This is a daunting question for nations like Naiku that have experienced multiple layers of property dispossession. Should Naiku’s program compensate people for property rights violations that occurred from 1910 to 2009 (includ- ing only T3 and T4) or from 1996 to 2009 (including only T4)? Or should the state include all violations that have occurred since 1810 (the period encom- passing T2, T3, and T4)? Numerous countries have dealt with these hard questions. In 1994, after the fall of apartheid in South Africa, the new political dispensation contended with apartheid-era land theft by enacting the Land Restitution Act, which instructs the state to compensate individuals and communities for a “right in land or portion of land dispossessed after 19 June 1913 as a result of past 41. Jahangir Saleh, Property Rights Institutions and Investment 7 (World Bank Policy Research, Working Paper No. 3311, 2004); see also Stein Holden & Hailu Yohannes, Land Redistribution, Tenure Insecurity, and Intensity of Production: A Study of Farm Households in Southern Ethiopia, 78 LAND ECON. 573, 575 (2002) (finding an inverse relationship between the willingness of farmers to invest in long-term improvements on their land and the perception of insecurity based on land reform in flux in Ethiopia). 42. Eric A. Posner & Adrian Vermeule, Transitional Justice as Ordinary Justice, 117 HARV. L. REV. 761, 785 (2004) (“If all claims are immediately recognized and announced to the world, then both losers and winners will know the extent of their existing property rights, and they will invest and trade accordingly.”). 43. Id. (“As this description suggests, the amount of uncertainty {in investment} is a decision variable. A state can reduce uncertainty by requiring that all claims be filed within six months, as Czechoslovakia did, and by using expedited procedures . . . . If all claims are immediately recognized and announced to the world, then both losers and winners will know the extent of their existing property rights, and they will invest and trade accordingly.”). 80 58 UCLA LAW REVIEW DISCOURSE 65 (2010) racially discriminatory laws or practices.”44 Similarly, in the Balkans prior to the NATO bombing of the region in 1999, thousands of Kosovo Albanians were forced to flee their homes due to a Serbian-led ethnic-cleansing campaign.45 The interim U.N.-led civilian administration (the United Nations Mission in Kosovo or UNMIK) enacted a reparations program that gave any person who was dispossessed of a property right as a result of discrimination between March 23, 1989, and March 24, 1999 a right to restitution in kind or compensation.46 In Germany, the government enacted the Law on Settlement of Open Property Questions in September of 1990, which permits return of property that was expropriated by the East German government after 1949 as well as property expropriated by the Nazis between January 30, 1933, and May 8, 1945.47 In 1991, the Hungarian government enacted the First Compensation Law for owners subject to Communist-era expropriations;48 and in 1992, the gov- ernment passed the Second Compensation Law, which mandates compensation for Jews dispossessed by Nazi Germany and ethnic Germans expelled from Hungary in the wake of the Nazi retreat.49 Australia’s reparations program— instituted by the Aboriginal Land Rights (Northern Territory) Act of 1976—set aside a twenty-year period (1976–1996) during which the state allowed abo- riginal people to make a collective property claim to crown land that had been stolen from them during conquest.50 Like many countries before it, Naiku must also decide which property violations it will rectify. It can return to the property status quo that existed 44. Restitution of Land Rights Act 22 of 1994, as amended by Act 48 of 2003, § 2(1) (S. Afr.); see also S. AFR. CONST. 1996 § 25(7) (“A person or community dispossessed of property after 19 June 1913 as a result of past racially discriminatory laws or practices is entitled, to the extent provided by an Act of Parliament, either to restitution of that property or to equitable redress.”). 45. NOAM CHOMSKY, ROGUE STATES: THE RULE OF FORCE IN WORLD AFFAIRS 34 (2000) (describing the situation in Kosovo prior to the NATO bombings). 46. On Residential Property Claims and the Rules of Procedure and Evidence of the Housing and Property Directorate and the Housing and Property Claims Commission, U.N. MIK Reg. No. 2000/60, § 2.2 (Oct. 31, 2000). 47. See Jessica Heslop & Joel Roberto, Property Rights in the Unified Germany: A Constitutional, Comparative, and International Legal Analysis, 11 B.U. INT’L. L.J. 243, 257 (1993). 48. See generally ISTVAN POGANY, EUROPE AND CHANGE: RIGHTING WRONGS IN EASTERN EUROPE 155–65 (1997) (describing property restitution and compensation schemes in Hungary). 49. See Gutiérrez, supra note 4, at 130–34. 50. If an aboriginal group was able to prove traditional ownership, it was entitled to receive an inalienable freehold title held by a corporate land trust. See Hinchman & Hinchman, supra note 35, at 23, 36–37 (stating how the Aboriginal Land Rights (Northern Territory) Act, 1976 (Austl.) was a radical departure from Milirrpum v. Nabalco Pty. Ltd. (1971), 17 F.L.R 141, which required an economic attachment to the land in order to make a property claim. Also, most claims were exceedingly difficult to establish, and by the end of the twenty-year period, aboriginal people possessed 43 percent of the northern territory (where 15 percent of the Australian aboriginal population lived)). Property and Transitional Justice 81 at T1, T2, or T3, each of which has its own specific virtues and vices, which I review below. 1. Return to T1 or T2 The most compelling argument for returning to T1 is the principle of first possession: first in time, first in right.51 The Alim are the first known human inhabitants of the land and are the only group in present-day Naiku to have an indisputable claim to just acquisition. But, an addendum to the first-in-time principle is Locke’s labor theory, which posits that being first to occupy is not sufficient to constitute ownership because land ownership results only when labor is mixed with the land.52 Under Locke’s labor theory, the Alim owned, and thus only have a potential claim to, lands that were under cultivation or being used in other productive ways. Similarly, the virtue of returning to T2 is that at T2, both the Alim and Alieu occupied the land on an equitable basis because the chief distributed land fairly according to each family’s needs. There are, however, specific obstacles to returning to T1. It has been about two hundred years since the Alim exclusively inhabited Naiku in T1 and just less than one hundred years since the Alieu nation ruled in T2. Due to consistent intermarriage, the two communities are no longer distinct, so returning to T1 is logistically impossible. But, since the Alieu community endures, a community claim is appropriate, and all present members would bene- fit from the compensation distributed by Layla’s government. In contrast, with individual or family claims (or claims of an extinct community), the original claimants are deceased, so the beneficiaries are their heirs, who are potentially numerous and difficult to locate. Consequently, given the significant passage of time, a return to T2 is logistically possible only because the Alieu nation is a surviving, functional entity that can identify its members and distribute com- pensation for the betterment of all. Even if a return to T1 were logistically possible, it is not clear whether it would be a morally appropriate solution. Jeremy Waldron’s supersession thesis argues that circumstances change such that what was rightfully owned at one 51. See, e.g., JESSE DUKEMINIER & JAMES E. KRIER, PROPERTY 3 (5th ed. 2002) (discussing acquisition of property by first possession or “[f]irst come, first served.”). See generally Lawrence Berger, An Analysis of the Doctrine That “First in Time Is First in Right”, 64 NEB. L. REV. 349 (1985) (discussing first possession as the dominant method of establishing property rights and its continued relevance, and examining cases in which first possession is the dominant rule). 52. See JOHN LOCKE, SECOND TREATISE OF GOVERNMENT 18 (C.B. Macpherson ed., Hackett Publishing 1980) (1690). 82 58 UCLA LAW REVIEW DISCOURSE 65 (2010) point may not be rightfully owned at a later time.53 He reasons, for example, that if someone steals another person’s car, this is a continuing injustice, so compensation provided for the car is not meant to rectify something that hap- pened in the past, but rather to address a present ongoing injustice.54 Waldron tempers his claim by acknowledging that various circumstances erode even continuing entitlements. Consider, for instance, two communities— M and O. Each community has its own water source; thus, M has a moral right to exclude O from using M’s water source, and O has a moral right to exclude M from use of O’s water source. But if a drought dries up M’s water source, then O no longer has a moral right to exclude M because the exclusion could lead to mass suffering and death in the M community. Even if M invaded O’s waterhole by force prior to the drought, once M’s water source has dried up, M has a moral right to continue using O’s well because it is immoral to deprive someone of something necessary for her survival. Consequently, the initial injus- tice perpetrated against O (that is, the invasion) is superseded by circumstance (the drought).55 In the case of Naiku, the Alim owned land at T1, a time of plenty. At T2, drought and population explosion caused land scarcity—the impetus behind the Alieu nation’s attack on the Alim in 1810. Thus, according to the supersession thesis, subsequent circumstances superseded and morally justified the Alieu’s use of Alim lands. According to the supersession thesis, returning to the property status quo at T1 and making the Alim the exclu- sive beneficiaries of the reparations or restoration program would therefore be morally unjust. Returning to T2 also has it problems, namely evolving land ownership systems. In Naiku, land was not owned individually in fee simple until T3 when the British arrived, divided the land, and deeded each plot. Under the Alieu nation at T2, the chief owned all the land and parceled it out to his subjects according to their needs. The system introduced by the British, however, persists today, so a return to T2 would be problematic because a 53. Jeremy Waldron, Settlement, Return, and the Supersession Thesis, 5 THEORETICAL INQUIRIES L. 237, 245 (2004) (“[I]n certain sequences of circumstances, dispossession may not continue to count as an injustice even though the events that led to it undoubtedly were an injustice. And if the dispos- session does not continue to count as an injustice, then reversion cannot be conceived as an appropriate remedy.”). 54. See id. at 246 (“Justice may make reference to the past, through principles of desert and Lockean entitlement; but its primary focus is on the present—present-day people, present-day resources— and on the circumstances of the present inasmuch as they affect who should get what.”). 55. See Jeremy Waldron, Superseding Historic Injustice, 103 ETHICS 4, 23 (1992) (“If, for example, P acquires an oasis in conditions of plenty, she acquires (i) a right to use it freely and exclude others from its use so long as water remains plentiful in the territory, and (ii) a duty to share it with others on some fair basis if ever water becomes scarce. The right that is (permanently) acquired. . . is thus circumstantially sensitive in the actions it licenses.”). Property and Transitional Justice 83 different land ownership structure existed then. One way to reconcile the dif- ferent land ownership systems would be to treat occupancy rights at T2 as ownership rights in fee simple for purposes of the restoration or reparations program.56 This is what the South African state did in its reparations efforts, for example. 2. Return to T3 A return to T3 is the most logistically feasible option if the state intends to compensate individuals rather than groups. When the British arrived in 1910, they introduced a property system based on written deeds and a land registry system. Therefore, determining who owned which parcel of land after T3 would not be nearly as challenging as returning to the period before British conquest. Also, since British settlers were dispossessed in 1996, concerns about identifying who should receive compensation are attenuated because most owners are still alive; if they are not, it will be simpler to track down their heirs than the heirs of those who passed away one hundred or more years ago. The primary downside of returning to T3 is the unfairness of the extant property distribution. T3 marked the advent of colonialism, which forced Africans into economic and political subordination. Returning to T3 would ignore the injustices of colonialism, cement the consequent illegitimate eco- nomic gains accrued by whites, and likely erect a permanent color hierarchy in Naiku. Most importantly, the African majority could resist (if not violently rebel against) a return to T3 because that property status quo was unfair and illegitimate. Leonid Polishchuk argues that “if private property rights are not sufficiently broadly recognized in the society as legitimate and fair, it makes the property rights regime unstable. This instability precludes efficient relocation of assets, and as a result expected efficiency gains of private ownership fail to materialize.”57 If Naiku wants its system of private property to thrive, the option of returning to T3 is not feasible. 56. See South Africa Extension of Security of Tenure Act 62 of 1997 (S. Afr.) (providing that the right in land “may have been established by occupation of the land for a substantial period. It is not limited to a right recognized by law. It is not limited to ownership rights, and it may include certain long-term tenancy rights and other occupational rights”); DEP’T OF LAND AFFAIRS, S. AFR., WHITE PAPER ON SOUTH AFRICAN LAND POLICY (1998). 57. Leonid Polishchuk, Distribution of Assets and Credibility of Property Rights (Mar. 2, 2009) (unpublished manuscript on file with author). 84 58 UCLA LAW REVIEW DISCOURSE 65 (2010) C. Option Three: Creating a New Property Status Quo If implemented correctly, creating a new property status quo has the poten- tial to level the playing field, to equalize wealth, and to promote stability.58 The state can implement wealth redistribution through the tax and transfer system or by redistributing real property through land equalization, a concept that I develop in this Subpart. 1. Tax and Transfer Louis Kaplow and Steven Shavell argue that “redistribution through legal rules offers no advantage over redistribution through the income tax system and typically is less efficient.”59 Through the tax and transfer system, the government can broadly reallocate wealth from more financially astute citizens to those with greater financial vulnerability. Redistribution through taxation could include wealth in the form of real, personal, and intangible property, which would allow Naiku to move beyond the narrow problem of land dispossession and to address the larger problem of asset inequality. This is a particularly attractive remedy for nations that have moved from an agrarian-based economy, in which 58. There is a vast body of literature confirming that land reform can increase economic growth and decrease the potential for instability. See SAMUEL P. HUNTINGTON, POLITICAL ORDER IN CHANGING SOCIETIES (2006); RUSSELL KING, LAND REFORM: A WORLD SURVEY (1977); ROY L. PROSTERMAN & JEFFREY M. RIEDINGER, LAND REFORM AND DEMOCRATIC DEVELOPMENT (1987); Daron Acemoglu et al., Reversal of Fortune: Geography and Institutions in the Making of the Modern World Income Distribution, 117 Q.J. ECON. 1231 (2002); Daron Acemoglu et al., The Colonial Origins of Comparative Development: An Empirical Investigation, 91 AM. ECON. REV. 1369 (2001); Timothy Besley & Robin Burgess, Land Reform, Poverty Reduction, and Growth: Evidence From India, 115 Q.J. ECON. 389 (2000); Klaus Deininger & Lyn Squire, New Ways of Looking at Old Issues, 57 J. DEV. ECON. 259, 287 (1998); Edmundo Flores, Issues of Land Reform, 78 J. POL. ECON. 890 (1970); Herschel I. Grossman, Production, Appropriation, and Land Reform, 84 AM. ECON. REV. 705 (1994); T. David Mason, “Take Two Acres and Call Me in the Morning”: Is Land Reform a Prescription for Peasant Unrest?, 60 J. POL. 199 (1998); Karl Ove Moene, Poverty and Landownership, 82 AM. ECON. REV. 52 (1992); Edward N. Muller et al., Land Inequality and Political Violence, 83 AM. POL. SCI. REV. 577 (1989); Bruce M. Russett, Inequality and Instability: The Relation of Land Tenure to Politics, 16 WORLD POL. 442, 453 (1964) (arguing that land reform and stability in underdeveloped countries is a necessary component, though not a guarantee, of political stability); Klaus Deininger & Pedro Olinto, Asset Distribution, Inequality, and Growth (World Bank Policy Research Working Paper No. 2375, 2000); Klaus Deininger & Songqing Jin, Land Rental Markets as an Alternative to Government Reallocation?: Equity and Efficiency Considerations in the Chinese Land Tenure System 22 (World Bank Policy Research Working Paper No. 2930, 2002); Klaus Deininger, Songqing Jin & Hari K. Nagarajan, Land Reforms, Poverty Reduction, and Economic Growth: Evidence From India 1 (World Bank Policy Research Working Paper No. 4448, 2007). 59. Louis Kaplow & Steven Shavell, Why the Legal System Is Less Efficient Than the Income Tax in Redistributing Income, 23 J. LEGAL STUD. 667, 667 (1994). Property and Transitional Justice 85 access to land is vital, to an industry- or services-based economy, in which access to land is less important.60 Taxation is not a perfect solution, however. First, many transitional states have weak tax bureaucracies that are not effectively able to collect taxes and to transfer them to beneficiaries in the form of cash payments or social pro- grams.61 Second, higher taxation gives the wealthy an incentive to transfer wealth outside of the country and can dampen the incentives to create wealth domestically.62 Third, while a reparations or restoration program mandates a one-time asset transfer to beneficiaries, tax and transfer programs redistribute wealth gradually, leaving beneficiaries vulnerable to changing political winds over time.63 Layla’s government has an incentive to announce a substantial tax and transfer program to quell present discontent concerning land inequality. But, while her political administration may be genuinely committed to cor- recting past wrongs using redistributive programs, future administrations may neglect such programs or cancel them altogether.64 This is the problem of time inconsistency: A present promise of future performance will not necessarily be honored. Time inconsistency is more likely to be a problem when beneficiaries constitute a politically powerless group because they cannot use the political system to influence future administrations to continue tax and transfer programs. But, problems associated with time incon- sistency can even affect politically powerful groups like the Alieu in certain instances. For example, in some countries, international economic organiza- tions, such as the International Monetary Fund, pressure local politicians to drastically reduce government spending in order to balance the country’s budgets and thereby increase their capacity to repay international loans.65 This coercion reduces the amount of funds available for use in the state’s redis- tributive programs. 60. W.W. ROSTOW, THE STAGES OF ECONOMIC GROWTH: A NON-COMMUNIST MANIFESTO (3d ed. 1990) (describing the five stages of economic development). 61. See Richard M. Bird & Eric M. Zolt, Redistribution Via Taxation: The Limited Role of the Personal Income Tax in Developing Countries, 52 UCLA L. REV. 1627 (2005). 62. Id. at 1669. 63. Robin Broadway, Nicolas Marceau & Maurice Marchand, Investment in Education and the Time Inconsistency of Redistributive Tax Policy, 63 ECONOMICA 171, 186–87 (1996) (describing the effects of time inconsistency in redistributive tax policy on education and wealth disparity). 64. See Alfred L. Brophy, Some Conceptual and Legal Problems in Reparations for Slavery, 58 NYU ANN. SURV. AM. L. 497, 554 (2003) (discussing the decline in support for affirmative action policies because, with the passage of time, these policies are no longer viewed as a form of reparations for slavery). For further discussion about why affirmative action policies have suffered from time inconsistency, see, for example, BARBARA R. BERGMANN, IN DEFENSE OF AFFIRMATIVE ACTION 8 (1996). 65. See James H. Weaver, What Is Structural Adjustment?, in STRUCTURAL ADJUSTMENT: RETROSPECT AND PROSPECT 8 (Daniel M. Schydlowsky ed., 1995) (“Virtually all IMF agreements have an expenditure reducing component.”). 86 58 UCLA LAW REVIEW DISCOURSE 65 (2010) A fourth problem with taxation is that tax and transfer programs will not be sufficient in certain states because the novel attributes of land make its actual transfer essential. In his empirical evaluation of public opinion related to land in South Africa, James Gibson found that “70% . . . of African respondents . . . agreed that ‘Land is special: Having land is more important than having money.’”66 Land is special because it often has an unquantifiable cultural value that derives from the key role it plays in individual and group identity. Communities are often spiritually and emotionally tied to the land where their ancestors are buried.67 As a result, although a group or individual may have been dispossessed long ago, dispossessed owners can still have a deep cultural connection to particular parcels of land that does not erode with the passage of time. Land is also unique because it is a highly visible sign of wealth; as a result, perceptions about inequality may not shift without the significant transfer of real property.68 Additionally, land is special because it is the basis of sovereignty. If an oppressed indigenous majority does not reclaim land that was unjustly dispossessed by its colonizers, political independence can ring hollow.69 Finally, in some societies, land is the most important means of production, making access to land the primary way to counteract poverty and marginalization.70 Therefore, while some states can address inequality resulting from past land theft through tax and transfer programs, others require land redistribution. 2. Land Redistribution At T5, the government of Naiku can choose not to pursue a reparations or restoration program and thus dispense with the work of identifying who owned or occupied particular land parcels and the work of locating their heirs. Naiku’s government can instead implement a program to redistribute real property that is not focused on vindicating past rights in land. The objective of land redistribution in Naiku would be to provide greater access to land based 66. See JAMES L. GIBSON, OVERCOMING HISTORICAL INJUSTICES: LAND RECONCILIATION IN SOUTH AFRICA 40 (2009). 67. Waldron, supra note 55, at 4, 19–20 (qualifying his theory that property rights may fade with time by noting that property rights may not fade when the dispossessed entity is a tribe or community and the land taken is important to that group’s sense of identity). 68. See generally Carol M. Rose, Crystals and Mud in Property Law, 40 STAN. L. REV. 577 (1988) (discussing the importance we place on property and clear property rules, given the significance of property ownership as a signal of our economic and social standing). 69. See Kaumbi, supra note 17, at 28. 70. Moene, supra note 58, at 52, 53, 61 (“The amount of land relative to the population and the demand for labor in urban areas are shown to influence strongly the economic and social impact of land redistribution.”). Property and Transitional Justice 87 on an individual’s current socioeconomic status or membership in a previously disadvantaged group. For example, in the redistributive prong of South Africa’s land reform strategy—the Land Redistribution for Agricultural Development (LRAD) program—a citizen can qualify for a state grant to purchase land if he or she is an adult from a previously disadvantaged group who intends to engage in full-time farming and can contribute a minimum of R5,000 ($665) towards the acquisition.71 To secure land for redistribution, the state can either rely on willing sellers to whom the state pays a mutually agreed-upon price, or in the alternative, it can rely on eminent domain. In the latter case, the state determines the amount of just compensation given the circumstances, and the landowner has the right to appeal to the courts if she thinks the amount is inadequate. Land equalization is a specialized type of land redistribution program that is best suited for societies in which land is a key economic commodity and in which historical injustice has led to multiple ownership claims to the vast majority of the nation’s land parcels. It is a way for a society to wipe the land ownership slate clean and start over. Land equalization places individuals and corporations on equal footing without heeding the Marxist call to abolish all private property. The difference between land equalization and taxation is that the former focuses on the redistribution of land rather than all wealth. In addition, land equalization mitigates time inconsistency concerns by delivering benefits to individuals and communities in a shorter timeframe. The most important dif- ference between land equalization and land redistribution is their respective moral starting points. The starting point for land equalization is that everyone is entitled only to his or her fair share of land. Under land redistribution, the state assumes current owners are entitled to their current land holdings, so to acquire their land, the state must wait for current owners to willingly sell their land, or the state can invoke eminent domain and pay the current owners just compensation. A system of land equalization in Naiku might look like this: Every citizen who reaches the age of eighteen by a certain date will be allocated a certain number of points, and each point is worth a certain amount of money. The primary caretakers for people under the age of eighteen will qualify for a set amount of additional points per dependent. The government and corporations 71. MINISTRY FOR AGRIC. & LAND AFFAIRS, S. AFR., LAND REDISTRIBUTION FOR AGRICULTURAL DEVELOPMENT: A SUB-PROGRAMME OF THE LAND REDISTRIBUTION PROGRAMME (2000), available at http://www.sarpn.org.za/documents/e0000008/20010604SibandaAppendix.pdf. The dollar figures were calculated using an exchange rate of 7.5 to 1. 88 58 UCLA LAW REVIEW DISCOURSE 65 (2010) will also receive predetermined amounts of points. Through a participatory process involving government, civil society, and international experts, Naiku will devise a system by which each parcel of land, both publicly and privately owned, will be assigned a certain number of points based on its value. This determination will account for factors such as the price paid, fair market value, existing improvements, circumstances of acquisition, and the strategic impor- tance of the land. These factors will ensure that land acquired in good faith is treated differently than land that was transferred under dubious circumstances. Imagine that Naiku decides to allocate 100 points to each citizen. If X presently owns land worth 150 points, then she has two choices. She can either pay for the 50 points that she holds in excess of her 100 point alloca- tion or relinquish her title to land worth 50 points in order to bring her land worth down to 100. In either case, to increase accountability, the money or land would be deposited into an internationally monitored land redistribution account. A corporation should receive points based on its contribution to soci- ety (determined by the number of people it formally employs, the amount of money invested in society, etc.); unlike individuals, corporations could not receive money from the redistribution account but would be required to pay into it.72 In contrast, if Y owns land worth 25 points, she can take a cash or an in- kind payment worth 75 points, acquire land worth 75 points, or receive some combination of both from the redistribution account in order to raise her point total to the allocated 100. In-kind payments are crucial to land equalization because the process of choosing from a wide array of viable options makes citizens active agents in the process of transformation.73 All in-kind payment options would have predetermined point allocations and could include things like specialized vocational training, higher education for two generations, priority in an existing housing program, and access to subsidized credit.74 The list of in-kind payments would have to be tailored to the abilities of the gov- ernment and the needs of its people.75 The land equalization process would unfold in two rounds. The purpose of the first round would be to build up the redistribution account. Private citi- zens who own property in excess of 100 points would decide whether to place land or money into the redistribution account, and the government and corpo- rations would place land in excess of their predetermined allocation of points 72. The tradeoff is that this may reduce a corporation’s ability to create jobs. 73. See Atuahene, From Reparation to Restoration, supra note 15, at 1447–50 (arguing that choice plays a large role in making people active agents and restoring their visibility). 74. Id. at 1448–49. 75. Id. at 1448–50. Property and Transitional Justice 89 into the account as well. In the second round of the process, the state would distribute land, money, and in-kind payments to those with less than 100 points. A national lottery would determine the order in which people spent their points. After the initial allocation of property rights through the point system, there would be no restraints on alienation, so people would then be free to trade at will. Land equalization’s main strength is its potential to reorder the property status quo and to level the playing field.76 It is not designed to restore a prior status quo, so those who have never owned land are not excluded from the redistributive program as they are in restoration or reparations programs. A shortcoming shared by both land equalization and land redistribution programs is that wealth accumulated as a result of past land theft can be transferred to non-land-based investments such as securities, thereby achieving land ownership equity, but not asset equity.77 Consequently, the state should implement tax and transfer programs alongside land equalization and redistribution programs. III. THE PROCESS OF CHOOSING FROM THE AVAILABLE OPTIONS I have discussed the options available to Naiku and other states that have the political will to address past property theft. In this Part, I will argue that the process a state uses to choose between the available options is vitally important. More specifically, I argue that when choosing between options, the state should use a highly participatory process involving a broad swath of the pol- ity because this will increase the perceived and actual legitimacy of the resulting property status quo. As it stands now, groups of elites often decide how states address past theft. For example, in South Africa’s Land Restitution Program, both the decision to compensate only those who were dispossessed of a right in land after 1913, as well as the process the state would use to compensate citizens, were made primarily with the involvement of political parties and experts with limited direct consultation of average citizens.78 Likewise, in Kosovo, the decision to provide restitution in-kind or compensation only to persons dispossessed 76. The strengths of land equalization are discussed in Part II.B, supra. 77. The downsides of land equalization are enumerated in Part II.B, supra. 78. See Restitution of Land Rights Act 22 of 1994, as amended by Act 48 of 2003, §§ 2(1)(b), 2(3), 4 (S. Afr.); Heinz Klug, Participating in the Design: Constitution-Making in South Africa, 3 REV. CONST. STUD. 18, 20 (1996). 90 58 UCLA LAW REVIEW DISCOURSE 65 (2010) between March 23, 1989, and March 24, 1999, was made by international actors, with limited involvement of average citizens. 79 States that limit the participation of average citizens in their decisionmak- ing processes fail to avail themselves of several advantages of broad participation. First, because one primary purpose of addressing past theft is to increase the legitimacy of the state and present property arrangements, curtailing public participation in the process can place the perceived legitimacy of the program at risk. The evidence shows that people are likely to believe that the outcome of a legal process is legitimate even if it is unfavorable to them, as long as the process involved fair procedures and was conducted by the appropriate authori- ties;80 Tom Tyler and others have proven that “the opportunity to express one’s opinions and arguments, the chance to tell one’s own side of the story, is a potent factor in enhancing the experience of procedural justice, even when the opportunity for expression really accomplishes nothing outside the proce- dural relationship.”81 Second, true participation results in the devolution of power to average citi- zens and hence serves as a check on the power of traditional decisionmakers. For example, if the process is transparent and highly participatory, it is more difficult for program administrators to perform corrupt acts because people have been allowed behind the closed doors and are actively watching. Third, a public conversation can help to ground citizens’ expectations in reality. Some transitional states cannot afford to give everyone compensation, so the public conversation can provide people with information about exactly what resources are available and what programs the state can offer given its limited resources. Fourth, direct citizen participation introduces a unique perspective not available when the decisionmaking process is dominated by elites. A broadly representative group of people is better suited than elites to know the 79. See On Residential Property Claims and the Rules of Procedure and Evidence of the Housing and Property Directorate and the Housing and Property Claims Commission, U.N. MIK Reg. No. 2000/60, § 3 (Oct. 31, 2000). 80. See Tom R. Tyler & E. Allan Lind, A Relational Model of Authority in Groups, 25 ADVANCES EXPERIMENTAL SOC. PSYCHOL. 115, 149, 162–64 (1992). See generally JOHN THIBAUT & LAURENS WALKER, PROCEDURAL JUSTICE: A PSYCHOLOGICAL ANALYSIS (1975); TOM R. TYLER, WHY PEOPLE OBEY THE LAW (2006). 81. Id.; see also Robert Folger, Distributive and Procedural Justice: Combined Impact of “Voice” and Improvement on Experienced Inequality, 35 J. PERSONALITY & SOC. PSYCHOL. 108 (1977) (describing an experiment involving distribution of monetary rewards by a manager and finding that, on a measure of procedural fairness, “voice workers” (workers who expressed opinions on fairness) expressed more satisfaction with the allocation process than “mute workers” (workers who gave no statements of their opinions)); Stephen LaTour, Determinants of Participant and Observer Satisfaction With Adversary and Inquisitorial Modes of Adjudication, 36 J. PERSONALITY & SOC. PSYCHOL. 1531 (1978) (finding that the satisfaction with an adjudicative procedure was impacted by procedural fairness and the opportunity for presentation of all relevant information to the decisionmaker). Property and Transitional Justice 91 population’s preferences. Lastly, democracy is strengthened when people partici- pate in deciding issues that directly affect them.82 When states decide to address past theft through an inclusive, highly participatory process, they must be ready to navigate around several poten- tial pitfalls. First, the process can become time-consuming given the number of people who should be involved and the challenges of synthesizing the information received. But, by investing time in participatory procedures on the front end, the state can receive the dividends in the form of increased legitimacy at the back end. 83 Second, meaningful public participation requires significant resources that many cash-strapped transitional states cannot provide. Thus, it is crucial for states to involve civil society and international organi- zations in managing the process, which can reduce state expenditures and increase transparency. A third potential drawback of a highly participatory process is the difficulty of facilitating a conversation that adequately balances participation and deliberation precisely because participation has the potential to undermine deliberation. A common solution to the deliberation- participation paradox is for the organizing entity to choose community representatives.84 But, there is no guarantee that the people the entity chooses will be accountable to, or representative of, the larger public. Fourth, a public conversation about past property theft could serve to inflame extant divisions and ethnic- or religious-based hatred lurking just below the surface. But, it is not necessarily bad that talking about past injus- tices has the potential to cause latent animosities to boil up to the surface, so long as the conversation leads to a solution that will assuage the ethnic rancor moving forward. Fifth, the very concern a public conversation is intended to address—a lack of legitimacy—may prevent people from participating in the decisionmaking process. If people are discontent because of an illegitimate property distribution, this could result in apathy and disengagement rather than a determination to find a solution. Lastly, and most problematically, even if a state manages to facilitate a meaningful public conversation, there is no guar- antee that the output of the conversation will affect the ultimate decision. The entire process can devolve into a propaganda campaign designed to give the illusion of power sharing when in actuality the state is carrying on with 82. See CAROLE PATEMAN, PARTICIPATION AND DEMOCRATIC THEORY 31 (1970). 83. Id. at 60–61 (citing the Port Townsend Terminal case and the time and money the gov- ernment lost by only consulting organized groups and excluding others). For a discussion about participatory procedures, see Atuahene, Things Fall Apart, supra note 15, at 829, 859–65. 84. Bruce W. McClendon & J.A. Lewis, Goals for Corpus Christi: Citizen Participation in Planning, 74 NAT’L CIVIC REV. 72 (1985). 92 58 UCLA LAW REVIEW DISCOURSE 65 (2010) business as usual, and the decisions are being made by those in power with no regard for what average citizens desire.85 While the importance of involving the public in the political deci- sionmaking process is largely undisputed in the literature,86 the level of control the public should have in the decisionmaking process is a very controversial matter. At the very basic level of participation, power holders aim to educate the public about options, rights, and responsibilities, but information flows in one direction.87 This is not true participation. A moderate participation level involves token participation from certain stakeholders who are informed or consulted, but the present power holders are not forced or inclined to truly integrate the knowledge and suggestions of these participants.88 Alterna- tively, a few handpicked citizens who are not accountable to their communities may be invited to join a decisionmaking body. In both situations, the commu- nity has no true opportunity to decide. A high participation level is achieved when participants exercise a significant amount of control over both the process and outcome;89 this is the type of public participation envisioned in this Article. To achieve a high participation level, a state must use a bottom-up approach for defining the relevant public groups, which may include stakeholders such as political parties, bureaucrats, community organizations, average citizens, and experts.90 To ensure significant buy-in, the state must include both organized groups and citizens not affiliated with particular groups.91 The end goal is to make the final decision about how to address past property violations in collaboration with a diverse, representative group of citizens. 85. Cheryl Simrell King, Kathryn M. Feltey & Bridget O’Neill Susel, The Question of Participation: Toward Authentic Public Participation in Public Administration, 58 PUBLIC ADMIN. REV. 317, 322 (1998) (using focus groups in northeast Ohio—comprised of administrators and citizens—to examine the perceived effectiveness of attempts to incorporate public participation in administrative decisionmaking). 86. See Ortwin Renn et al., Public Participation in Decision Making: A Three-Step Procedure, 26 POL’Y SCI. 189 (1993). 87. See Sherry R. Arnstein, A Ladder of Citizen Participation, 35 J. AM. PLANNING ASS’N 216, 217–18 (1969). 88. Id. at 217, 219–20. 89. Id. at 217, 221–23. 90. See JOHN CLAYTON THOMAS, PUBLIC PARTICIPATION IN PUBLIC DECISIONS: NEW SKILLS AND STRATEGIES FOR PUBLIC MANAGERS 61–62 (1995) (noting how the state must not choose to engage only certain groups while excluding others with contrary views). 91. Before inviting organized groups, however, the state must explore how democratic each group is and whom each one represents. See Walter A. Rosenbaum, The Paradoxes of Public Participation, 8 ADMIN. & SOC’Y 355, 372 (1976) (“An almost universal finding in participation studies is that groups or individuals active in such programs (1) represent organized interests likely to have been previously active in agency affairs, (2) include a large component of spokesmen for other government agencies, (3) represent a rather limited range of potential publics affected by programs, and (4) tend toward the well-educated, affluent middle- to upper-class individuals.”). Property and Transitional Justice 93 CONCLUSION One of the most important issues facing transitional states is what they should do about past property violations. There is, however, a paucity of scholarship that explores the options a transitional state has. I examined the potential courses of action for a hypothetical country called Naiku in order to highlight the challenges many transitional states confront. Countries like Naiku, with the political will to address past land theft, have three options: (1) maintaining the present property status quo, (2) fully or partially returning to a prior property status quo, or (3) creating a new property status quo alto- gether. The main conclusion of this Article is that no matter which option a transitional state chooses, its decisionmaking process is crucial. Ensuring legiti- macy and lasting results requires a well-informed, inclusive public dialogue rather than a less time-consuming, less costly process involving only elites. For example, a state may decide to maintain the current property status quo because it does not have the bureaucratic capacity to redistribute property. While this is an important decision, what is more important is the participa- tory nature of the decisionmaking process. If the property status quo has been sullied by asset-based inequalities resulting, in large part, from past land dispossession, then a top-down decision not to reorder property arrangements can result in widespread resentment and feelings of injustice. In contrast, if the decision is a result of a highly inclusive, public dialogue, studies show that the population will likely perceive it as just.92 In sum, this Article aims to further the literature about how transitional states can deal with past property violations. While I created the nation of Naiku to streamline the discussion, the problems that Naiku faces are very real and deserve further intellectual inquiry. 92. Tyler & Lind, supra note 80, at 162–64. work_b46pij2zrnbc5pl5ydp4srgdye ---- Untimely Resnais: Muriel's Disarticulations of Justice Untimely Resnais: Muriel’s Disarticulations of Justice Laura McMahon, Gonville and Caius College, University of Cambridge (lcm31@cam.ac.uk) Abstract: Alain Resnais’s 1963 film Muriel ou le temps d’un retour (Muriel, or the Time of Return) has been read in terms of a failure to engage with the historical and political issues surrounding the Algerian War – a failure viewed by Susan Sontag as a consequence of Resnais’s favouring of aesthetics over politics. This essay reconsiders Muriel beyond the terms of this perceived privileging of aesthetic abstraction over political engagement, and looks at ways in which the spatio-temporal organization of the film is bound to forms of political critique. Drawing on Jacques Derrida’s thinking of justice and Gilles Deleuze’s emphasis on the topological dimensions of Resnais’s cinema, I argue that Muriel’s differential, interruptive configurations of history and place carve out a time and space for justice that refuses ontologization, reanimating encrypted traces of Algeria’s traumatic history of decolonization and resisting the mournful memory-work of the French nationalist account. Keywords: Resnais; Derrida; Deleuze; deconstruction; justice; mourning In a current global political context haunted by the spectre of the ‘ non-person ’ – a context which includes illegal yet state-sanctioned acts of war, imprisonment, torture and rendition flights – revisiting Alain Resnais’s 1963 Muriel ou le temps d’un retour (Muriel, or the Time of Return), a film which has at its absent centre a woman tortured by the Film-Philosophy 20 (2016): 219–234 DOI: 10.3366/film.2016.0012 f Laura McMahon. The online version of this article is published as Open Access under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial Licence (http://www.creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/3.0/) which permits non-commercial use, distribution and reproduction provided the original work is cited. For commercial re-use, please refer to our website at: www.euppublishing.com/customer-services/ authors/permissions. www.euppublishing.com/loi/film 219 French during the Algerian War of Independence (1954–62), may appear timely. Indeed, the timeliness of various acts of revisiting and return is precisely what is at stake in Muriel, as indicated by the title of the film itself. Yet, Resnais’s film has often been judged untimely in its failure to engage directly with the immediate events of the Algerian War (Muriel was released just a year after the end of the conflict. See, for example, Boudjedra 1971, p. 27; see also Gauch 2001, pp. 47–57). For some critics, this failure crystallizes in the film’s refusal to represent Muriel – absent from image and sound, Muriel is neither seen nor heard; we know nothing of her life beyond the event of her torture; we never witness events from Muriel’s point of view. Nor does the film appear to engage with the military and political realities of the Algerian War itself (in contrast to, say, Gillo Pontecorvo’s The Battle of Algiers [La Bataille d’Alger], released in 1966, three years after Muriel). Though censorship in France at the time of Muriel’s release limited representation of the Algerian War (evidenced most clearly by the ban upon Jean-Luc Godard’s Le Petit Soldat [1960]), it has also been suggested that such restrictions were perhaps not obstructive enough to warrant the degree of narrative ellipsis adopted by Resnais’s film (Stora, 1998, p. 41; quoted in Gauch, 2001, p. 48n4). Thus while Muriel foregrounds reflections on questions of memory, testimony and forgetting, Muriel’s absent-present position within the film becomes indicative of what Suzanne Gauch calls the ‘ disappearing text ’ of the war (2001, p. 53). 1 On this reading, a failure to give a voice and image to Muriel is understood as part of the film’s broader failure to engage with the historical and political issues surrounding the conflict in Algeria (viewed, as in Susan Sontag’s reading of the film, as a consequence of Resnais’s favouring of aesthetics over politics [1963, pp. 23–7]). In this essay, I wish to reconsider Muriel beyond the terms of this perceived privileging of aesthetic abstraction over political engagement, and to look at ways in which the spatio-temporal organization of the film is bound to forms of political critique. 2 Specifically, I argue that the film’s differential, interruptive configurations of history and place can be read as carving out 1. For an important discussion of French cinema, including Muriel, as ‘ so often fantasized as empty of Algerians ’, see Austin, 2007 (p. 182). 2. Here my argument is indebted to the recuperation of the political impetus of Muriel proposed by Leo Bersani and Ulysse Dutoit, 1993, pp. 181–208. To their reading I add in particular a focus on the differential dynamics of justice. Since writing this essay in 2011, I have encountered further very useful discussions of the political dimensions of Muriel, including Max Silverman’s reading of the film’s ‘ palimpsestic structure ’ of ‘ concentrationary memory ’ (Silverman, 2013), and Maria Flood’s analysis via Butler’s reflections on ‘ grievability ’ (Flood, forthcoming). Film-Philosophy 20 (2016) 220 a time and space for justice, through a perpetual revisiting and reanimation of historical and testimonial traces. Though my primary focus here is on justice rather than mourning, the two issues are deeply interlocked, as Jacques Derrida suggests in Specters of Marx: to render justice is to resist any terminable work of mourning, to refuse to ontologize death (1994, p. 97). Here an opening to justice might be understood as what Ranjana Khanna, drawing on Derrida in her discussion of Algerian history, gender and representation, calls a form of ‘ critical melancholia ’, which brings into focus ‘ the inassimilable, the barely incorporated, and the melancholic traces that in turn cause damage to the force field of mournful national history that fails to introject them ’ (2008, p. xvii). 3 In resonance with Khanna’s diagnosis of ‘ barely incorporated ’ histories, which she herself links to a call for justice, Muriel is a film in which melancholic traces of the inassimilable surface at critical moments to fissure the protective epistemological screens of (imperial) memory. The fictional crises of Muriel – the event of torture and the failures and fault-lines of memory that the film explores – are indicative of a wider historical reality – of French atrocities in Algeria and of collective amnesia surrounding these acts – that is melancholically resistant to memorialization, in that it perpetually calls into question the mournful memory-work of the nation-state. 4 As I turn to focus on issues of justice in Muriel, I seek to bear in mind Khanna’s linking of justice to the ‘ melancholic remainder[s] ’ of Algeria’s traumatic history of decolonization (2008, p. 15), to the encrypted traces that a French nationalist account fails to introject. What would it mean for Muriel – a film – to render justice? This would be a notion of justice understood not in a judicial or legal sense but rather in terms that conjoin the aesthetic to both the political and the ethical. In considering a mode of justice rendered by Resnais’s film, I follow Derrida’s thinking of justice as incommensurable, as interruptive of the present, as always to come. In contrast to the timeliness of a return to Muriel suggested above, justice for Derrida can only ever be untimely, for justice operates beyond ontology – it is that which is addressed to those no longer 3. Khanna argues fruitfully for the ways in which Derrida’s Algerian heritage shapes his thinking of deconstructive justice (2008, pp. 31–67). Derrida’s thought thus intersects with Muriel via a range of interwoven concerns. 4. As Khanna notes, collective amnesia in the aftermath of the Algerian War was encouraged and sanctioned by French amnesty laws, first introduced through the Evian Accords of 1962. This highlights ‘ the very particularity of the Algerian situation […] in terms of the forms of exception, marginalization, erasure, and amnesia that characterize it […] ’ (2008, p. 3, p. 8). Muriel’s Disarticulations of Justice 221 or not yet present (hence the centrality of the spectre and the ‘ hauntological ’ in his reflections on justice [Derrida, 1994, p. 97]). Justice is thus anachronistic, incalculable, out of joint (a phrase which Derrida borrows from Hamlet) (Derrida,1994, p. 18). Such a notion of justice would appear apposite for a consideration of Muriel – not only does the film circulate around the untimely absence of its eponymous subject, but, in its irrational cuts and interruptive editing, it also deploys discontinuous forms of temporality, configuring time itself as out of joint. 5 It is not only time that is out of joint in Muriel but space as well. As the film cuts erratically between various locations, space becomes dislocated, disjunctive and incalculable. This spatio-temporal discontinuity appears to exemplify the association between ‘ non-chronological time ’ and ‘ non-localizable relations ’ proposed by Gilles Deleuze in his reading of Resnais (2005, p. 119). 6 Yet Deleuze goes on to suggest that space is not the main concern of Resnais’s cinema: ‘ The image no longer has space and movement as its primary characteristics but topology and time ’ (2005, p. 121). Though space and movement remain central to my consideration of Muriel, I aim to take up Deleuze’s focus on topology in connection with my discussion of time. Topology emphasises both the shifting dimensions of objects under conversion and underlying properties of interconnectedness, offering a fertile framework for considering the spatialization of processes of memory, encryption and association (Colman, 2011, pp. 163–178). In what follows, I thus focus on the event of Muriel’s torture – and, by extension, questions of ethical and political responsibility – as configured both hauntologically and topologically by the film. In this sense, the topological emphasis of Deleuze’s account of Resnais’s cinema adds to the hauntological contours of Derrida’s thinking of justice, and vice versa. 7 Therein may lie the possibility of viewing Muriel in terms of an incommensurable justice addressed to a being (or beings) no longer or not yet present – a justice which, in dialogue with the durational and cartographic dynamics of cinema, is (dis)articulated here not only temporally but spatially too. Though the Algerian War figures as a latent presence in earlier films by Resnais, such as Night and Fog (Nuit et brouillard, 1955), Hiroshima mon amour (1959) and Last Year at Marienbad (L’Année dernière à 5. On untimely cinema in general, see Jodi Brooks and Therese Davis (Eds.), 2012. This edited issue includes a discussion of untimeliness in Resnais’s Last Year at Marienbad, which draws principally on Badiou’s thinking of the event (Ling, 2012). 6. For a Deleuzian reading of time and untimeliness in Resnais, see Boljkovac, 2013. 7. On broader connections between Deleuze and Derrida, see Patton and Protevi (Eds.), 2003. Film-Philosophy 20 (2016) 222 Marienbad, 1961), Muriel constitutes his most explicit (albeit indirect) engagement with the conflict (Wilson, 2006, pp. 88–89). The film is set in Boulogne-sur-mer in France, focusing on the lives of Bernard ( Jean-Baptiste Thierrée), who has recently returned from fighting in the Algerian War, and his stepmother Hélène (Delphine Seyrig). Hélène has invited her former lover Alphonse (Jean-Pierre Kérien) to visit; he has brought with him his current lover Françoise (Nita Klein), under the pretence that she is his niece. Alphonse’s visit allows for an exchange of conflicting memories with Hélène relating to a love affair that they had just before the outbreak of World War II. As Alphonse reminisces about the past, he pretends that he has spent time living and working in Algeria. The space of Hélène’s apartment thus provides the locus for a reanimation of memories of Algeria and of World War II, both imagined and real. The film situates these domestic dramas of recollection in relation to shots of the city either in ruins or rebuilt, recalling the large-scale destruction and reconstruction that took place in Boulogne during and after World War II. The city thus bears the traces of its own traumatic history, the background against which the memories of the various characters will be revisited and recast, as the film explores le temps d’un retour of its title. ‘ Muriel ’ is the name given to an Algerian woman whom Bernard apparently witnessed being tortured to death by French soldiers during the Algerian war – an event that he claims not only to have seen but to have taken part in. While pretending to Hélène that Muriel is the name of his fiancée, Bernard spends his time attempting to document the event of Muriel’s torture, assembling old journal entries and photographs, filming around Boulogne and viewing home movie footage from Algeria. Yet Bernard’s efforts to archive the event reveal only the failure of such an undertaking: as he throws his camera into the sea, the film gestures self-reflexively to the unbridgeable gap between truth and representation. As Robert – a fellow ex-soldier and now a member of the OAS (Organisation de l’armée secrète) – who was also complicit in the torture of Muriel, remarks to Bernard: ‘ You want to tell the story of Muriel? Muriel is something which can’t be told. ’ This resistance to retelling is foregrounded in the scene in which Bernard’s tape is switched on by Françoise, playing back a cacophony of male laughter which we may infer to be the sounds of Muriel’s torture. But Bernard rushes to rip the tape out of the machine, silencing the disturbing sounds. He goes on to shoot Robert dead – an act that hovers problematically between a form of retribution for Muriel, a disavowal of his own responsibility, and a further violent silencing of the past. In its disjointed narrative arc, the film arguably risks allowing Bernard’s failed documentation of the torture of Muriel to figure as symptomatic of a Muriel’s Disarticulations of Justice 223 psychological (rather than political) crisis of guilt and memory, thus relegating Muriel, and the Algerian War, to a symbolic function divorced from historical referentiality. As Gauch puts it: ‘ Bernard’s co-option and erasure of Muriel’s battered body in the tale of his personal torment repeats a violence that the film just begins to acknowledge ’ (2001, p. 51). Muriel’s aesthetics of fragmentation and ellipsis further threatens to obscure the truth of Muriel’s suffering, and, by extension, the historical real of atrocities committed by the French during the Algerian War. Indeed, Gauch suggests that it is the very ambiguity of Muriel’s place – and of Algeria – in the film that facilitates this stylized aesthetics of disjunction (2001, p. 51). The criticism here is that by enabling a particular aesthetics, Muriel disables a certain politics. Yet what I wish to suggest, through further examination of the film’s hesitations over forms of historical remembrance, is that Muriel’s aesthetics of discontinuity plays a key role in its politics and ethics of engagement. Spectral Returns In probing the limits of filmic representation, Muriel raises fundamental issues of memory, testimony and knowledge, asking questions about what it is possible to see, hear, remember and know, in ways that recall Jacques Rancière’s notion of the ‘ distribution of the sensible ’ (Rancière, 2006). Through Bernard’s attempts to accumulate what he refers to at one point as ‘ preuves ’ – the term resonates in its double meaning in French as both ‘ proof ’ and ‘ film rushes ’ – Muriel self-reflexively explores specific links between evidence, testimony and film. In so doing, the film raises doubts, as Emma Wilson suggests, about ‘ the possibilities of testifying, of bringing grief and guilt into the open ’ (2006, p. 91). Muriel gestures to cinema’s impotence in the face of any such efforts of recuperation. The fragility of audio and visual forms of evidence is emphasized – both in Bernard’s discarding of the tape and in a filmic image (possibly of Algeria) that we see melting when projected in Bernard’s studio. The vulnerability and ephemerality of these testimonial media – of tape and of celluloid – furnish a form of self-referential comment on the limits of representation, the mutability of ‘ proof ’ and the instability of acts of memorialization. As such, the film moves from an avowed emphasis on the stabilizing certainties of ‘ evidence ’ towards the differential dimensions of the trace. In an early scene, Hélène chastises Bernard for leaving a coffee pot on one of her antique tables, asking how she will sell it if it has a scratch; a close-up shows Bernard’s hand brushing the surface of the table, but a slight residue remains. As a concern with physical marks on objects anticipates an engagement with the psychical traces of culpable acts, Muriel redistributes the sensible, signalling a Film-Philosophy 20 (2016) 224 surfeit of testimonial remainders that will surface to unsettle the film’s epistemological frames. Such an engagement with the uncertainties of memorialization points to Muriel’s hauntological reconfiguring of time. This is exemplified not only by the film’s interruptive, non-linear editing (for example, as Celia Britton notes, the abrupt insert of daytime shots of Boulogne within a scene set at night [Britton 1990, 37]) but also by particular moments in which the link between image and sound becomes disjointed; as Britton observes: ‘ the dialogue from one shot is carried over to the next, where it acts as a jarring background to an entirely different image ’ (Britton 1990, 37). This desynchronized structure also occurs in reverse, for example, when we hear a conversation between Hélène and Alphonse over images of Bernard and Françoise in the street outside the flat, before the film shows Hélène and Alphonse in conversation. Image and sound seem further at odds when apparently banal moments are punctuated by a strident musical score (Gauch, 2001, p. 50), as though the film itself were out of synch. Such formal disarticulations and deferrals appear to give cinematic body to Derrida’s configuration of the spectral as ‘ outside of any synchrony ’ (1994, p. 7). Here image and sound are rendered out of joint, as the film enacts a perpetual interruption of the present moment, elaborating a non-synchronic structure that ushers in a surfacing of ‘ melancholic remainders ’. The mise-en-scène further emphasises this anachronistic dimension through the eclectic mixture of antiques in Hélène’s apartment. As the film shifts from a register of ontology to hauntology, the present is held in suspension, opening to a perpetual revisiting and reshaping of certain memories (Derrida, 1994, p. 7). 8 This hauntological reconfiguring of time comes to the fore in the scene in which Bernard recounts the torture of Muriel while watching what appears to be an extract of his own home movie footage of Algeria. Through the conceit of the film-within-the-film, Muriel reminds us once more of the instability of ‘ proof ’, as images here are not what they seem. The grainy footage of French soldiers in Algeria – relaxed, laughing and apparently at ease with the locals – is undercut by the visceral violence of Bernard’s commentary. At stake here is not so much an aesthetics of juxtaposition as one of interrelatedness – as Leo Bersani and Ulysse Dutoit suggest, the sequence invites us to draw (delayed) connections between image and sound, for example, between the soldier diving and Bernard’s description of Muriel looking ‘ as if she had been left under water ’ (1993, 8. On amnesia, repetition and deferral in Muriel, see Croombs 2010. Muriel’s Disarticulations of Justice 225 p. 196). 9 What the sequence brings into focus is a logic of inextricability that binds the visible scenes of military life on-screen to the invisible scene of torture off-screen. Bernard claims to have been unaffected by the torture of Muriel at the time: after viewing her corpse, he slept well. Yet the apparent indifference of his account is undermined not only by the distress in his voice but by one detail in particular: ‘ Muriel’s eyes were not closed. ’ Echoing the same words in Bernard’s diary (glimpsed when Alphonse rifles through his papers), this phrase recalls an earlier detail of Bernard’s description of Muriel during her torture: ‘ She stared straight at me. Why me? ’ This memory also resonates, by inversion, through Bernard’s anxious commands to his girlfriend Marie-Do not to close her eyes – a form of ghostly, differential repetition that is exacerbated by Bernard’s references to Muriel as his girlfriend. 10 Singling him out during the event and perpetually returning to call him to account in its aftermath, Muriel’s gaze haunts Bernard, ceaselessly reminding him of his complicity in the crime of her torture (Gauch, 2001, p. 51, p. 55). This spectral gaze, the gaze of another who is no longer present, places Bernard’s time – and the time of the film itself – out of joint, holding Bernard to account. Yet such a gaze is one which cannot be returned; it is ‘ without any possible symmetry, without reciprocity ’, signalling an infinite demand (Derrida and Stiegler, 2002, pp. 120–1). An incalculable responsibility is thus posed here in excess of Bernard’s capacity to respond. And Muriel’s gaze figures a calling to account not only of Bernard, but also, by extension, of France, a nation haunted by the unsettled spectre of Algeria and by a demand for justice resisting ontologization, restlessly refusing to be attached to any one time or place. 11 Yet the risk of abstraction remains: consigning Muriel’s experience – and Algeria, by extension – to the realm of the spectral may still be viewed as politically disabling. In an analysis of Muriel alongside films such as Chris Marker’s La Jetée (1962) and Claude Chabrol’s Le Boucher (The Butcher, 1970), Emily Tomlinson draws on Derrida’s thinking of spectrality in order to address French cinema’s ‘ hauntological ’ engagement with Algeria. Critical of a tendency in these films to decontextualize the events of the Algerian War, Tomlinson contends that, through a series of metaphorical operations, such films ‘ appropriate 9. Bersani and Dutoit argue that this sequence circumscribes a call to responsibility that extends to the viewer, implicating us in this uneasy proximity between the ordinary and the unimaginable (1993, p. 196). 10. On differential repetition in Muriel, see Bersani and Dutoit 1993, p. 199. 11. On Muriel’s dynamic of ‘ ghostly return ’, see Hill 1992, p. 797. Film-Philosophy 20 (2016) 226 the pain of torture ’ via a ‘ generalized ‘ hauntology ’ ’ whereby ‘ the spectre of colonial brutality is no longer perceptible as such ’ (2002, pp. 46–7). Tomlinson argues persuasively that Muriel’s spectral operations abstract from historical specificity. Yet I wish to suggest here that while the film invokes this hauntological register, it remains attentive to traces of the historical real; indeed, this very attentiveness takes place through a hauntological engagement with the disjointedness of testimonial recognition and historical remembrance. As Gauch suggests, Resnais’s choice of the story of an Algerian woman tortured by the French displays an awareness of contemporaneous journalistic and testimonial accounts of the Algerian War (2001, pp. 54–5). Gauch cites the cases of Djamila Bouhired and Djamila Boupacha, who were both tortured and raped by French soldiers. Such cases gained considerable public attention in France at the time: Simone de Beauvoir was instrumental in seeking justice for Boupacha; she then co-authored a book about Boupacha’s experience, which appeared in 1962, the same year as the making of Muriel (Halimi and de Beauvoir, 1962). The film engages with the details of torture in ways that suggest familiarity (on the part of both Resnais and the scriptwriter, Jean Cayrol) with such testimonies. Bernard’s disturbing account of the state of Muriel’s corpse (‘ it was as if she had been left under water ’; ‘ With blood all over her body and in her hair … burns on her chest ’) implies torture by water and possibly electricity too – methods that were commonly used during the Algerian War. The film also suggests a conscious engagement with the particular gendered dimension of such atrocities. Marnia Lazreg’s study of practices of torture deployed by the French during the Algerian War has emphasized that Algerian women were routinely raped by French soldiers, to the extent that ‘ [a]lthough rape could take place without torture, torture seldom took place without rape ’ (2008, p. 160). Though Bernard’s account makes no explicit reference to rape, it notes at one point that Muriel’s clothes were torn off. Elsewhere in the film, Bernard’s perverse references to Muriel as his fiancée suggest ways in which she is configured erotically in his memory and imagination, intimating again the sexual dimension of her torture. 12 It may be that considerations of censorship influenced Resnais’s decision to allow the suggestion of Muriel’s rape to remain ambiguous. It may be that this indirect approach indicates a potential failure of the film’s responsibility. Yet, it is also possible to read the film’s resistance to the ontologization of the event as opening a time and space in which ‘ melancholic remainders ’ may be called forth, 12. See Britton 1990, p. 46, and O’Brien 2000, p. 60. Muriel’s Disarticulations of Justice 227 allowing that which has been historically encrypted to surface through the deferrals and dislocations within Bernard’s testimony and within the film itself. In evocation of the slippages and displacements of testimonial detail, Muriel operates not only critically but also hauntologically, in attentiveness to a historical real that ghosts the frame – implicitly invoked yet never fully present. In this sense, the film’s spectral operations, though resistant to ontology, may be seen to elaborate a form of (anachronistic) justice to the historical real. What Muriel gives us to understand is that the encryption of the events of the Algerian War in France’s collective memory exhibits a deep-rooted structure of spectrality that is played out here. Through images of Boulogne, suspended between ruins and reconstruction, the film implicitly positions the collective guilt attached to Algeria as haunted by other painful memories – explicitly of World War II, implicitly of Vichy. 13 Through Hélène’s and Alphonse’s conflicting reconstructions of their love affair, the film articulates, as Naomi Greene suggests, ‘ the climate of self-serving half-truths, of deliberate amnesia, that, in the early 1960s, characterized French memories of the Vichy era ’ (1999, p. 46). By bringing into focus a chain of amnesiac operations, Muriel ensures that its indirect engagement with French atrocities in Algeria is inseparable from its implicit invocation of a collaborationist past. And although the film foregrounds recent events in Algeria, it intimates the ways in which these events are necessarily haunted by a history of colonial violence. When Françoise tells Bernard that she has been acting in a film about a war in 1830 in which ‘ everyone died ’, this is followed by a shot of the deserted dining table; no further elaboration is given, but the date references the French invasion of Algiers and the beginning of imperial expansion into Algeria. The scene appears to bear out Tomlinson’s suggestion that the Algerian War was always already ‘ a spectral conflict ’, inextricably bound to past atrocities, to the irrepressible logic of the revenant (Tomlinson, 2002). Links between French collaboration and colonialism are emphasized further during the dinner at the restaurant, in which anecdotes and gastronomical reflections sit alongside fleeting references to deportation, Indochina and Algeria (including Alphonse’s racist comment about Arabs). Françoise’s tale of live lobsters cooked in boiling water is preceded by Roland de Smoke’s story of a subsiding house (‘ It’s new, it’s empty, and we’re waiting for it to fall down ’). Together, these seemingly disparate remarks gesture to histories of 13. Cayrol’s own experience of betrayal as a member of the Resistance and internment in a camp during World War II arguably informs such connections here. Film-Philosophy 20 (2016) 228 violence enshrouded by a modernized France. In its summoning of so many revenants of a colonialist and collaborationist past, Muriel foregrounds an inescapable logic of differential repetition that gestures beyond the fictions of its amnesiac crises towards the traumatic real of historical recurrence. Thus Muriel resists any restoratively mournful reconstruction of the past – in Deleuzian terms, it refuses to actualize the past in a ‘ recollection-image ’ (Deleuze, 2005, p. 119). Rather it elaborates what Deleuze describes, with reference to Resnais, as ‘ paradoxical hypnotic and hallucinatory sheets [of time] whose property is to be at once a past and always to come ’ (2005, p. 119). This ‘ always to come ’ is as important to Deleuze’s reading of Resnais as it is to Derrida’s conception of justice. 14 For Deleuze, Resnais’s cinema ‘ prevents the past from being debased into recollection ’ (2005, p. 120); similarly, for Derrida, justice takes place through a resistance to any petrification of the past, by way of a perpetual opening to that which is ‘ to come ’ (1994, p. 65). This opening to a justice-to-come is akin to what Derrida has called midmourning (1987, p. 355), a hauntological suspension of the introjective and incorporative dimensions of mourning – what Alessia Ricciardi describes as an ‘ ethically and politically energized space ’, ‘ a domain of remembrance in which the subject is perpetually re-exposed to history rather than removed from it ’ (2003, p. 34). The dislocated rhythm of midmourning and differential repetition that Muriel elaborates ensures a ceaseless reanimation of the subject’s relation to historical time. In configuring temporally immediate events as saturated by untimely correspondences, Muriel proposes a hauntological model of eventhood, whereby the present is always already haunted by the past and by so many possible future returns. Topological conversions Muriel gestures to the traces of atrocity in terms that are not only hauntological but topological too. As Marie-Do’s view through a kaleidoscope fills the screen, multiplying images of Bernard, the film reflexively signals its aesthetics of topological transformation – a pattern of morphing and redistribution visualized in space. As we have seen, Deleuze points to the topological aspects of Resnais’s cinema – a cartographical tracing of realms of being, which might be read in Muriel as an implicit mapping of the shifting psychical and political co-ordinates of torture. In The Body in Pain, Elaine Scarry argues that torture itself is a 14. In his broader reflections on the time-image, Deleuze, like Derrida, invokes Hamlet: ‘ Time is out of joint ’ (2005, p. 39). Muriel’s Disarticulations of Justice 229 process of conversion: transforming suffering into the spectacle of power, it maximizes the perceptual world of the torturer, while aggressively reducing that of the prisoner (1985, pp. 27–38). Scarry elaborates the interrogative encounter between torturer and prisoner in topological terms: ‘ It is only the prisoner’s steadily shrinking ground that wins for the torturer his swelling sense of territory. The question and the answer are a prolonged comparative display, an unfurling of world maps ’ (1985, p. 36). Torture enacts a topology of contraction and expansion, a violent recasting of territories of being, which can be linked, I suggest, to the ‘ contracting/expanding tendencies ’ of Muriel’s organisation of space (Kite, 2009, p. 12). Drawing on Scarry in her reading of Muriel, Wilson suggests persuasively that the connection between the psychological effects of torture and the rest of the film may be viewed as one of ‘ inflection and contamination ’, rather than one of direct representation (2006, p. 100). Deleuze’s cartographical framing of Resnais allows for the dynamic of ‘ inflection and contamination ’ identified by Wilson here to be considered further via a particular emphasis on the political dimensions of Muriel’s territorial redistributions of the event of torture. Through a relational mapping of perceptual space, Muriel elaborates a topology of contraction and expansion that brings the continuously shifting contours of remembrance, amnesia and the historical real into view. Topological effects in Muriel signal a connection between ‘ the steadily shrinking ground ’ of the torture victim and the expansive ground of colonial, sovereign space. Through the disjunctive mapping of zones of Boulogne, enhanced by rapid, disconnective editing, the film is regularly set free from legible co-ordinates of location, with the effect that on-screen space appears to expand. For Claude Ollier, the film elaborates ‘ a kind of spiral or circle opening further and further out so that the whole film seems to be basically centrifugal with everything projected to the outside ’ (quoted in Britton, 1990, pp. 39–40); 15 similarly, Bersani and Dutoit suggest, ‘ Muriel is a wholly centrifugal film ’ that is ‘ constantly rushing away from a narrative centre never firmly established in the first place ’ (1993, p. 191). Bersani and Dutoit cite the scene in which a stranger asks a local woman for directions, having failed to recognize that he is in the city centre. (It is presumably with this scene in mind that Deleuze suggests that in Muriel, ‘ the new Boulogne has no centre ’ [2005, p. 112]). As the stranger’s confusion becomes indicative of the way in which legible space is disrupted in Muriel, a sense of place becomes dispersed through 15. Britton also addresses the centrifugal force of the film, linking this to the motif of the kaleidoscope (Britton 1990, 40). Film-Philosophy 20 (2016) 230 an apparently increasing extension of urban territory. This is the ever-expanding ground of the sovereign – the centrifugal unfurling of French metropolitan space, invoked by the film in order to map the perceptual and political co-ordinates of colonial power and its inverse. In contrast to the ‘ steadily shrinking ground ’ of Muriel, ever to remain hidden from view, the main characters (particularly Robert and Bernard, the perpetrators of Muriel’s torture) freely negotiate their way around the space of the city. 16 These topological effects of contrast and morphing are compounded by the mapping of space in Hélène’s apartment. Though at times the apartment appears to be configured in claustrophobic terms, it is a space which allows for what Scarry calls ‘ outward unfolding ’ (1985, p. 39) – Hélène moves sometimes frenetically to and fro inside the apartment yet she also moves freely out of the apartment (for example, on her multiple trips to the casino). The apartment is a place of experiential extension, bearing out what Scarry describes as ‘ the central, overwhelming characteristic of the domestic ’: that ‘ its protective, narrowing act is the location of the human being’s most expansive potential ’ (1985, p. 40). In the context of torture, however, ‘ the world is reduced to a single room or set of rooms ’ (Scarry 1985, 40). The topology of torture is such that the physical and perceptual space of the prisoner contracts. In Bernard’s account of Muriel’s torture, she is placed in the centre of the room, under the beam of Robert’s torch, so that the officers can ‘ get a better look ’; surrounded, she falls from a chair, her arm twisted. Such is the centripetally deforming force of torture – what Scarry calls the ‘ unmaking ’ of the world – a collapse of the world, a vertiginous folding inwards. Thus through a system of subterranean correspondences, Muriel weaves connections between what we see and what is excluded from view. A recurrent focus on goods in shop windows gestures to the accelerated rise of consumerism in France during the period of the Algerian War – a culture of mass commodification further signalled in the film by snippets of speech that parody advertising slogans (such as Alphonse’s claim that ‘ [s]ome people cope with stains better than others – I’m one of them ’, followed by a grin). In the apparent disconnection between these motifs of consumerism and the event of Muriel’s torture, the film appears to bear out what Kristin Ross has shown to be an ideological delineation of 16. Having watched Bernard’s film, Vieux Jean asks where Robert is now. Bernard says: ‘ He walks around Boulogne, like everyone else. ’ To which Vieux Jean replies: ‘ But so do you! ’ Muriel’s Disarticulations of Justice 231 narratives of Algeria’s ‘ dirty war ’ and decolonization from discourses of sanitized modernization in France in the 1950s and 1960s (Ross, 1995). 17 Yet the over-determined meanings at stake in Alphonse’s claim about stain removal – in particular the invocation of culpability and disavowal – are indicative of a topology insisting on links between the realms of metropolitan consumerism and colonialist subjugation. As B. Kite suggests of Bernard’s investigations around Boulogne: ‘ perhaps he films café patrons, shop windows, the sliding building that recurs throughout Muriel as a minor motif to indicate that these signs of consumer comfort are historically predicated on the ‘ not-here ’ of a colonial economy, on blood and exploitation ’ (2009, p. 19). As Muriel’s cartographical disjunctions and consumerist visions become indicative of the relation of metropolitan space to its largely unacknowledged outside, the film enacts a series of topological conversions, revealing the fatal interdependence of the realms of the torturer and the prisoner, and of the coloniser and the colonised. Here the spectral contours of Muriel’s topology become apparent. For, as Gauch contends, ‘ the film refuses to localize the crime ’ (2001, p. 55); it refuses to limit the event of Muriel’s death to any one particular place, thereby resisting what Derrida calls ‘ ontopology ’ (1994, p. 82). As such, Muriel elaborates what Derrida refers to as a ‘ topology of mourning ’, whereby mourning is understood as ‘ without reliable limit ’, that is, without ontologization in terms of either time or space (1994, p. 97). Thus, read hauntologically and topologically, a different picture of Muriel emerges. As the film gestures perpetually to a moment beyond the present and to a place beyond that which is on-screen – ‘ not now ’ and ‘ not here ’ – both time and space are rendered out of joint. Tracing events which refuse to be brought fully to representation, suspended as they are in an ethically and politically animated realm of ‘ midmourning ’, the film engenders a series of melancholic remainders that, as Khanna suggests, rupture the ‘ force field ’ of an officially mournful history. What Khanna calls ‘ critical melancholia ’ emerges in Muriel through a hauntological configuration of time and a topological shaping of space. Here the time and space of colonial sovereignty is revealed as intimately and fatally bound to the ‘ not now ’ and ‘ not here ’ of the history and location of subjugated others. By intimating such interrelatedness in spectral and 17. Revealing one particularly disturbing bleed between the realms of decolonisation and modernisation, Ross notes that the new electrical appliances featuring in French kitchens during that period doubled up as instruments of torture used by the French during the Algerian War (1995, p. 113). Croombs draws on Ross’s study in one of his readings of Muriel (Croombs 2010b). Film-Philosophy 20 (2016) 232 topological terms, le temps du retour of Resnais’s film disarticulates an untimely, incalculable form of justice. Through this hauntopological reading, Muriel can be retrieved, to a certain extent, from criticisms of its lack of political engagement. Yet the film’s politics remains framed from the position of metropolitan France, both as a work by a French filmmaker and in the bias of its setting. The reverberations of a colonial history can be deconstructed from within, as Muriel intimates, by opening dominant imperial epistemologies to a surfeit of melancholic traces; yet for justice to be rendered – disjunctively, incommensurably – beyond these epistemologies, it remains vital to revisit and envisage further times and spaces through which the voices and images of Algeria might resonate (see Austin 2012). BIBLIOGRAPHY Austin, Guy (2007). Representing the Algerian War in Algerian cinema: Le vent des Aurès. French Studies, 61 (2), 182–195. Austin, Guy (2012). Algerian national cinema. Manchester: Manchester University Press. Bersani, Leo and Dutoit, Ulysse (1993). Arts of impoverishment: Beckett, Rothko, Resnais. Cambridge, MA; London: Harvard University Press. Boljkovac, Nadine (2013). Untimely affects: Gilles Deleuze and the ethics of cinema. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. Boudjedra, Rachid (1971). Naissance du cinéma algérien, Paris: François Maspéro. Britton, Celia (1990). Broken images in Resnais’s Muriel. French Cultural Studies, 1 (1), 37–46. Brooks, Jodie and Davis, Therese (2012). Untimely cinema: Cinema out of time. Screening the Past, 35, http://www.screeningthepast.com/issue-35/ Colman, Felicity (2011). Topology. In Deleuze and cinema: The film concepts (pp. 163–178). New York and Oxford: Berg. Croombs, Matthew (2010a). Algeria deferred: The logic of trauma in Muriel and Caché. Scope, 16. http://www.nottingham.ac.uk/scope/documents/2010/february-2010/ croombs.pdf Croombs, Matthew (2010b). Algeria deferred: The logic of trauma in Muriel and Caché. Paper delivered at the Society for Media and Cinema Studies Conference, Los Angeles, 21 March 2010. Deleuze, Gilles (2005). Cinema 2: The time-image. (Hugh Tomlinson & Robert Galeta, Trans.). London: Continuum. Derrida, Jacques (1987). The post card: from Socrates to Freud and beyond. (Alan Bass, Trans., with an introduction and additional notes). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Derrida, Jacques (1994). Specters of Marx: The state of the debt, the work of mourning, and the New International. (Peggy Kamuf, Trans., with an introduction by Bernd Magnus & Stephen Cullenberg). New York; London: Routledge. Derrida, Jacques and Stiegler, Bernard (2002). Echographies of television: Filmed interviews. (Jennifer Bajorek, Trans.). Cambridge: Polity Press. Flood, Maria (forthcoming). France, Algeria and the Moving Image: Screening Histories of Violence (1962–2010). Oxford: Legenda. Gauch, Suzanne (2001). Muriel, or the disappearing text of the Algerian War. L’Esprit Créateur, 41 (4), 47–57. Muriel’s Disarticulations of Justice 233 http://www.euppublishing.com/action/showLinks?crossref=10.3366%2Fedinburgh%2F9780748646449.001.0001 http://www.euppublishing.com/action/showLinks?crossref=10.1177%2F095715589000100104 http://www.euppublishing.com/action/showLinks?crossref=10.1093%2Ffs%2Fknm064&isi=000247824900004 http://www.euppublishing.com/action/showLinks?crossref=10.1353%2Fesp.2010.0037 http://www.euppublishing.com/action/showLinks?crossref=10.1353%2Fesp.2010.0037 Greene, Naomi (1999). Landscapes of loss: The national past in postwar French cinema. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. Halimi, Gisèle, and de Beauvoir, Simone (1962). Djamila Boupacha. Paris: Gallimard. Hill, Leslie (1992). Filming ghosts: French cinema and the Algerian War. Modern Fiction Studies, 38 (3), 787–804. Khanna, Ranjana (2008). Algeria cuts: Women and representation, 1830 to the present. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Kite, B. (2009). Everything is just like you. Muriel DVD booklet (The Masters of Cinema Series, Argos Films), 5–23. Lazreg, Marnia (2008). Torture and the twilight of empire: from Algiers to Baghdad. Princeton, N. J.; Princeton University Press. Ling, Alex (2012). Parentheses in time: L’Année dernière à Marienbad (1961) as amorous event. Screening the Past, 35, http://www.screeningthepast.com/2012/08/parentheses-in- time-l’annee-derniere-a-marienbad-1961-as-amorous-event/ O’Brien, Alyssa (2000). Manipulating visual pleasure in Muriel. Quarterly Review of Film and Video, 17 (1), 49–61. Patton, Paul and Protevi, John (Eds.). (2003). Between Deleuze and Derrida. London: Continuum. Rancière, Jacques (2006). The politics of aesthetics: The distribution of the sensible, trans. Gabriel Rockhill. London: Continuum, 2006. Ricciardi, Alessia (2003). The ends of mourning: Psychoanalysis, literature, film. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Ross, Kristin (1995). Fast cars, clean bodies: Decolonization and the reordering of French culture. Cambridge, MA; London; MIT Press. Scarry, Elaine (1985). The body in pain: The making and unmaking of the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Silverman, Max (2013). Palimpsestic memory: The Holocaust and colonialism in French and Francophone fiction and film. New York and Oxford: Berghahn. Sontag, Susan (1963). Muriel ou le temps d’un retour. Film Quarterly, 17 (2), 23–7. Stora, Benjamin (1998). La gangrène et l’oubli. Paris: La Découverte. Tomlinson, Emily (2002). Torture, fiction, and the repetition of Horror: Ghost writing the past in Algeria and Argentina. PhD dissertation, University of Cambridge. Wilson, Emma (2006). Alain Resnais. Manchester: Manchester University Press. FILMOGRAPHY Chabrol, Claude (1970) Le Boucher (The Butcher). France/Italy. Godard, Jean-Luc (1960) Le Petit Soldat. France. Marker, Chris (1962) La Jetée. France. Pontecorvo, Gillo (1966) La Bataille d’Alger (The Battle of Algiers). Italy/Algeria. Resnais, Alain (1955) Nuit et brouillard (Night and Fog). France. Resnais, Alain (1959) Hiroshima mon amour. France/Japan. Resnais, Alain (1961) L’Année dernière à Marienbad (Last Year at Marienbad). France/Italy. Resnais, Alain (1963) Muriel ou le temps d’un retour (Muriel, or the Time of Return). France/ Italy. Film-Philosophy 20 (2016) 234 http://www.euppublishing.com/action/showLinks?crossref=10.1515%2F9781400823048 http://www.euppublishing.com/action/showLinks?crossref=10.1515%2F9781400883813 http://www.euppublishing.com/action/showLinks?crossref=10.1353%2Fmfs.0.0407&isi=A1992LQ61600013 http://www.euppublishing.com/action/showLinks?crossref=10.1353%2Fmfs.0.0407&isi=A1992LQ61600013 http://www.euppublishing.com/action/showLinks?crossref=10.1080%2F10509200009361479 http://www.euppublishing.com/action/showLinks?crossref=10.1080%2F10509200009361479 http://www.euppublishing.com/action/showLinks?crossref=10.1525%2Ffq.1963.17.2.04a00100 work_b4oinzqicbbppbskfgxxorwps4 ---- None work_b4r4jcf72rbahlamzswhe2jmoq ---- Abstract: In this study, Hume’s theory of justice is examined critically with respect to morality, politics, and society. In addition to that, Hume’s account of justice is questioned owing to the free rider problem. First, the relationship between morality and justice is investigated. Although Hume takes sympathy seriously in his early works, he does not take sympathy to be a sure foundation in his later works. Then, circumstances of justice are explained to find exact place and necessity of the virtue of justice. With the way of decon- struction, Hume shows the cases that the virtue of justice is needed. Justice is largely concerned with the environment and dispositions of persons. Next, the artificial character of justice will be explained. Then, Hume’s laws of justice will be given and assessed: stability of property, exchange of property by agreement, and performance of promises. It is argued that Hume’s laws of justice mostly relate to economic justice. The chief drive that causes individuals to act justly is disciplined self-interest. Self-interest should be organized for public utility. Laws of justice are created by human conventions. The primary sources of the investigation are: Hume’s A Treatise of Human Nature, [1739] 1978; An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, [1751] 1998 and Political Essays, 1994. Keywords: Hume, ethics, politics, economics; society, the rules of justice, the free rider problem. Öz: Bu çalışmada, David Hume’un adalet kuramı ahlak, siyaset ve toplum açısından eleştirel bir şekilde incelenmiştir. Bunlara ek olarak Hume’un adalet anlayışı bedavacılık sorunu sayesinde sorgulanmıştır. İlk olarak ahlak ve adalet arasındaki ilişki tahkik edilmiştir. Erken çalışmalarında Hume duygudaşlığı ciddiye alsa da sonraki çalışmalarında onu sağlam bir temel olarak görmez. Ardından adalet erdeminin tam yerini ve gerekliliğini belirlemek için adalet koşulları açıklanmıştır. Yapıbozum yoluyla Hume, adalet erdeminin gerekli olduğu durumları göstermektedir. Adalet büyük oranda insanların çevresiyle ve eğilimleriyle iliş- kilidir. Sonra, adaletin yapay yapısı açıklanacaktır. Sonra, Hume’un adalet yasaları verilecek ve değerlendi- rilecektir: mülkiyetin istikrarı, sözleşme yoluyla mülkiyet alışverişi ve ahde vefa. Hume’un adalet yasalarının ekseriyetle iktisâdî adaletle ilgili olduğu tartışılmıştır. Bireylerin adil davranmalarını sağlayan temel saik kontrol edilmiş kişisel çıkardır. Kişisel çıkar kamu yararına hizmet edecek şekilde düzenlenmelidir. Adalet yasaları insani uzlaşımlar sayesinde oluşturulmuştur. Araştırmanın başlıca kaynakları David Hume’un şu eserleridir: İnsan Doğası Üzerine Bir İnceleme, [1739] 1978; Ahlakın İlkeleri İle İlgili Bir Araştırma, [1751] 1998 ve Siyasi Denemeler, 1994. Anahtar Kelimeler: Hume, adalet kuralları, etik, siyaset, toplum, iktisat, bedavacılık sorunu. Research Assistant, Kırklareli University. enes.eryilmaz@klu.edu.tr © İlmi Etüdler Derneği DOI: 10.12658/M0279 insan & toplum, 2019, 9(1), 1-27. insanvetoplum.org Başvuru: 04.07.2018 Revize: 07.08.2018 Kabul: 10.08.2018 Online Basım: 30.11.2018 Enes Eryılmaz David Hume’s Account of Justice the journal of humanity and society insan toplum This study is the developed version of my thesis’s fourth chapter, see Eryılmaz, 2011. I sincerely thank Ahmet Zahid Demirciler, Halil Turan, Tacettin Turgay, and the anonymous reviewers for their constructive criticisms and valuable comments. insan & toplum 2 Introduction The problematic in Hume’s account of justice emerges when we test its capacity to overcome the free rider problem. The free rider problem occurs when the matter is about collective goods. The problem is roughly as follows: there are collective goods (e.g. public services such as streetlights) that everyone utilizes. Since everyone takes advantage of streetlights, everyone should contribute to the cost of this ser- vice. Otherwise streetlights would shut down for financial reasons. However, since persons utilize streetlights collectively, we cannot measure and invoice the cost one by one like domestic electric consumption. The free rider utilizes streetlights but does not contribute to the cost. The free rider thus thinks that everyone except me should contribute to the cost of streetlights. If I don’t pay, nothing happens to streetlights. So, she takes a free ride. Since the good is a collective one, the free rider cannot be found.1 A. T. Nuyen applies to the free rider problem in order to understand Hume’s account of justice in the article titled, “Hume’s Justice as a Collective Good” (Nuy- en, 1986). Nuyen considers that Hume sees and solves the problem with the no- tion of sympathy and moral education. However, it is known that Hume himself observes sympathy to be a slender basis so that he abandones it in his later works (Hume, 1998; Selby-Bigge, 1975, p. xxi; MacIntyre, 1984, p. 49). Thus, in this pa- per Hume’s account of justice will be examined from the point of view of the free rider. This investigation will show that Hume fails to overcome the free rider prob- lem in his account of justice. Neither sympathy nor public utility can convince the free rider. There is a serious gap in the foundation of justice. The free rider would not feel responsible to obey Hume’s laws of justice. Hume and Nuyen is so naïve with respect to the free rider problem. Justice and Morality Since the writing style of David Hume is not analogous to analytical, academic, and formalistic techniques of contemporary scholars, understanding his theses is a chal- lenging work. Perhaps, this is the fundamental reason of debates on his ideas relat- ed with epistemology, ethics, politics, and religion. The notion of justice is a typical indicator of this ambiguity in the philosophy of Hume. The first problem is whether 1 For the free rider problem in detail, see Hardin, 2013. Enes Eryılmaz, David Hume’s Account of Justice 3 justice is a moral issue or not. Some scholars claim that in Hume’s conception, jus- tice is not autonomous when ethics is considered, i.e. justice is a prudential issue. Others maintain that obeying the rules of justice is a moral subject. On the other hand, there is one more viewpoint that defends Humean conception of justice both as a moral and a prudential issue. The problem is not concerned with ethics in small communities, but as the population increases justice becomes a moral issue. Hume examines genealogy of justice in Book III of A Treatise of Human Nature.2 He starts his investigation with the question: “Why [do] we annex the idea of virtue to justice, and of vice to injustice” (Hume, 1978, p. 498). Hume inspects the source of justice in a hypothetical condition which is similar to the conception of state of nature: After men have found by experience, that their selfishness and confin’d generosity, acting at their liberty, totally incapacitate them for society; and at the same time have observ’d, that society is necessary to the satisfaction of those very passions, they are naturally induc’d to lay themselves under the restraint of such rules, as may render their commer- ce more safe and commodious. To the imposition then, and observance of these rules, both in general, and in every particular instance, they are at first induc’d only by a regard to interest; and this motive, on the first formation of society, is sufficiently strong and forcible. But when society has become numerous, and has encreas’d to a tribe or nation, this interest is more remote; nor do men so readily perceive, that disorder and confusion follow upon every breach of these rules, as in a more narrow and contracted society. But tho’ in our own actions we may frequently lose sight of that interest, which we have in maintaining order, and may follow a lesser and more present interest, we never fail to observe the prejudice we receive, either mediately or immediately, from the injustice of others; as not being in that case either blinded by passion, or byass’d by any contrary temptation. Nay when the injustice is so distant from us, as no way to affect our interest, it still displeases us; because we consider it as prejudicial to human society, and pernicious to every one that approaches the person guilty of it (Hume, 1978, pp. 498-499). In the first stage of a society, in a small community, if a merchant is not loyal to his promises, he could not do business with other individuals. However, in a country or a nation state, cheaters can easily find new customers. Free riders take part at that point. In a small community they could not free ride, because they get caught. But in a large society they can vanish without a trace. They can sustain their interests in the short term, but in the long-term knaves would fail. This “natural myopia” (Yellin, 2000, p. 378) puts obstacles in the way of private and public inter- est. Interest thus is not sufficient to motivate just actions in large societies.3 Here 2 Hereafter this book will be abbreviated as Treatise. 3 Of course, in our global world motivating persons to be just is much more difficult. Certainly, global insan & toplum 4 Humean sympathy takes the role; by sympathy the road to morality is prepared in the case of justice. People communicate their feelings thanks to sympathy, so no one can remain insensitive to injustice. David Hume explicates source of the moral- ity of just actions in the level of state: We partake of their uneasiness by sympathy; and as every thing, which gives uneasiness in human actions, upon the general survey, is call’d Vice, and whatever produces satis- faction, in the same manner, is denominated Virtue; this is the reason why the sense of moral good and evil follows upon justice and injustice. And though this sense, in the present case, be deriv’d only from contemplating the actions of others, yet we fail not to extend it even to our own actions. The general rule reaches beyond those instances, from which it arose; while at the same time we naturally sympathize with others in the sen- timents they entertain of us. Thus self-interest is the original motive to the establishment of justice: but a sympathy with public interest is the source of the moral approbation, which attends that virtue (Hume, 1978, pp. 499-500).4 For this reason, the status of virtue is assigned to justice and vice to injustice. Approval of public interest by sympathy is the starting place of justice in morality. Injustice is destructive to public interest. It is harmful to the interests of human beings indirectly. Therefore, the moral basis of justice is clear. Hume asserts that since justice is beneficial to humanity, the notion turns out to be an ethical virtue: “no virtue is more esteemed than justice, and no vice more detested than injustice; nor are there any qualities, which go farther to the fixing the character, either as amiable or odious” (Hume, 1978, p. 577). Hence, for Hume, justice grounds itself on public interest with the support of sympathy. In this way, people obey the laws of justice even if they do not have direct interests. Next, Hume relates sympathy to the public good. Moral approbation of justice and disapproval of injustice is possi- ble in this approach: [s]ince there is a very strong sentiment of morals, which in all nations, and all ages, has attended them, we must allow, that the reflecting on the tendency of characters and mental qualities, is sufficient to give us the sentiments of approbation and blame. Now as the means to an end can only be agreeable, where the end is agreeable; and as the good of society, where our own interest is not concern’d, or that of our friends, pleases only by sympathy: It follows, that sympathy is the source of the esteem, which we pay to all the artificial virtues (Hume, 1978, p. 577). justice need better justifications to be reached, because one cannot mention a society of nations. With the help of communication across the world, borders are very loose now. There should be a system of global ethic for individuals in a cosmopolitan world; see Küng, 1998. 4 For a summary of Humean sympathy see Cohon, 2010. Enes Eryılmaz, David Hume’s Account of Justice 5 Hence, the artificial virtue justice is possible thanks to the Humean sympathy. The conception of justice is obviously in accordance with Hume’s moral thought. Moreover, it can be said that “[u]nlike many contemporary political theorists, Da- vid Hume sought to ground his political philosophy on epistemological and mor- al foundations” (Church, 2007, p. 169). Likewise, Gilles Deleuze locates Hume’s conception of justice under ethics as well: “[u]nder the name of belief, we have a practise of the understanding, and under the form of social organization and justice, a theory of morality” (Deleuze, 1991, p. 32). Knud Haakonssen identifies Humean principles of justice with his normative rules too: “the basic rules of justice pertaining to property and contract come to be accepted as moral rules” (Haakons- sen, 1993, pp. 190-191).5 David Gauthier also confirms the relation of justice and morality in Hume’s ethical and political thought: “[a]rrangements may be expected to be useful to each person; therefore they are just. These arrangements may also be expected to have beneficial consequences; therefore they receive moral approval, and justice is a virtue” (Gauthier, 1979, p. 18). Sharon Krause formulates this idea as follows: “[w]hen we contemplate justice through the lens of sympathy, the moral sentiment of approbation arises in us” (Krause, 2004, p. 641).6 To understand Hume’s position on the relation of justice and ethics clearly, it is helpful to describe “first period”7 with the role of prudence and “second stage”, namely large society, with morality. In a small society, justice is more related with prudence because interests of individuals are present, and they can see their inter- ests. If they do not abide by the laws of justice and working together, they would in- stantly face the consequences. For instance: “[t]wo neighbours may agree to drain a meadow, which they possess in common; because ‘tis easy for them to know each others mind; and each must perceive, that the immediate consequence of his fail- ing in his part, is the abandoning the whole project” (Hume, 1978, p. 538). Neighbors accordingly comply with the rules that manage society. When the population is low, “prudence will be a sufficient motive to induce proper co-oper- ation. In the case of a collective good such as national defense, which affects the whole nation, prudence alone is not sufficient” (Nuyen, 1986, p. 51). Nuyen seeks to explicate the relation of prudence and morals in terms of justice: 5 Furthermore, Haakonssen argues that Hume was influenced from the eighteenth-century moral thouu- ght which is highly theological and teleological; see Haakonssen, 1993, pp. 190-191. 6 Krause also elaborates his understanding of Hume’s view of justice with emphasizing public interest: “[s] ympathy takes us beyond self-interest by communicating to us the pleasures and pains of others, thereby engaging our interest in broader concerns and ultimately in the common good” (Krause, 2004, p. 641). 7 The small community is examined in the beginning of this article. insan & toplum 6 An individual does not see that his or her refusal to pay will undermine national se- curity. A free rider believes that not too many people have the same idea. Prudence, therefore, tends to induce us to take a free ride. If we do pay our fair share in this case, the motive that induces us to do so is not prudence, but something like the sense of fa- irness based on the realisation that by not paying we are hurting others who are willing to pay. It is a sense of fair play based on an empathy we have for others (Nuyen, 1986, pp. 51-52). That is to say, sympathy is required in large societies to realize and reinforce the rules of justice. Because of this factual and historical experience, i.e., transition to a large society, just persons pass “from a narrow prudential perspective, that gave us a natural obligation to adjust our passions and concur in a scheme of conduct, to a moral point of view” (Taylor, 1998, p. 20). For this reason, the principles of justice constitute an ethical matter in nation states. Nuyen thinks that Hume solves the free rider problem by appeal to sympathy, but why does a free rider sympathize with others? If she has a fair or moral perspective, she would not free ride anyway. If she does not view others fairly and ethically, she would free ride altogether. It seems like sympathy is not a satisfactory concept to overcome the free rider problem. After that Hume reckons justice among artificial moral duties in the Political Essays: The second kind of moral duties are such as are not supported by any original instinct of nature, but are performed entirely from a sense of obligation, when we consider the necessities of human society, and the impossibility of supporting it, if these duties were neglected. It is thus justice or regard to the property of others, fidelity or the observance of promises, become obligatory, and acquire an authority over mankind (“Of the Origi- nal Contract,” 1994, p. 196). Unlike other passages, in this passage he highlights justice as a moral duty de- pending on the sense of obligation. Haakonssen interprets justice in line with duty and obligation as well.8 Yet the concept of moral duty or the sense of obligation does not make sense for the free rider. She thinks that it does not make any differ- ence if she would not obey the rules of justice, because everyone except she obeys 8 “In a social group where just behaviour is generally approved as good because it produces social utii- lity, people who in a particular case lack any motive for justice … will tend to have a motive supplied. Because everyone generally approves of just behaviour as if it sprang from a separate laudable motive, people lacking such a motive will feel morally deficient as compared with their surroundings and will come to disapprove of or hate themselves on that account. In this they will be reinforced by the disap- proval of their fellows. This self-loathing becomes the motive or the will by which people act justly as a matter of obligation” (Haakonssen, 1993, p. 191). Enes Eryılmaz, David Hume’s Account of Justice 7 the rules of justice. Although she is obligated to do his part in principle, it does not matter in practice. Public order is stable and economic system works adequately as long as free riders are in the minority. Moral duty and the sense of obligation is not a sufficient reason to force free riders to act justly. In the conclusion of the Treatise, Hume, however, stresses sympathy with public interest in the source of the morality of justice again: We may observe, that all the circumstances requisite for its [sympathy’s] operation are found in most of the virtues; which have, for the most part, a tendency to the good of society, or to that of the person possess’d of them. If we compare all these circumstan- ces, we shall not doubt, that sympathy is the chief source of moral distinctions; especi- ally when we reflect, that no objection can be rais’d against this hypothesis in one case, which will not extend to all cases. Justice is certainly approv’d of for no other reason, than because it has a tendency to the public good: And the public good is indifferent to us, except so far as sympathy interests us in it. We may presume the like with regard to all the other virtues, which have a like tendency to the public good. They must derive all their merit from our sympathy with those, who reap any advantage from them: As the virtues, which have a tendency to the good of the person possess’d of them, derive their merit from our sympathy with him (Hume, 1978, p. 618). However, Hume gives up employing the notion of sympathy in his later work, An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals (1751).9 In this passage of the Treatise (1739), this is the last usage of sympathy as the source of morals. Selby-Bigge un- derlines this change: “[t]he psychology of sympathy which occupies so much space in Bk. II, and on which so much depends in Bk. III of the Treatise, is almost entirely ignored in the [second] Enquiry” (Selby-Bigge, 1975, p. xxi). So, Hume does not see sympathy in the foundation of morality of just actions in the second Enquiry. Alasdair MacIntyre too discerns this abandonment. MacIntyre says that Hume in- vented the concept of sympathy to justify the rules of justice, but since sympathy is a “philosophical fiction” (1984: 49) it could not provide good reasons for people to obey the laws of justice.10 In Whose Justice? Which Rationality? MacIntyre rejects 9 Hereafter this book will be abbreviated as second Enquiry. 10 “In the Treatise Hume posed the question why, if such rules as those of justice and of promise-keeping were to be kept because and only because they served our long-term interests, we should not be justi- fied in breaking them whenever they did not serve our interests and the breach would have no further ill consequences. In the course of formulating this question he denies explicitly that any innate spring of altruism or sympathy for others could supply the defects of an argument from interest and utility. But in the Enquiry he feels compelled to invoke just such a spring. Whence this change? It is clear that Hume’s invocation of sympathy is an invention intended to bridge the gap between any set of rea- sons which could support unconditional adherence to general and unconditional rules and any set of insan & toplum 8 sympathy as a satisfactory motivation: “the sympathy which we do indeed feel for particular others on occasion will not furnish a motive for a regard for the rules of justice whomsoever they may protect” (MacIntyre, 1988, p. 307). Additionally, MacIntyre refuses interest as a justification of principles of justice: “neither inter- est nor sympathy seems able to explain why each one of us should approve of the rules of justice or of the administration of those rules by government” (1988, p. 306). Both Hume and Nuyen thus fail to overcome the free rider problem, because neither the concept of sympathy nor public good can persuade free riders. These arguments could not provide firm justification or motive in order to compel free riders to obey the laws of justice. They act only from self-interest and do not think about the rest. After leaving behind the principle of sympathy in the Treatise, Hume focuses on the principle of utility to supply ethical basis of the concept of justice in the second Enquiry. He preferred public interest in the Treatise to ground the morality of justice, but in the second Enquiry Hume employs the notion of utility. David Miller draws an attention to this nuance: “Hume uses ‘the public interest’ in the Treatise and ‘utility’ in the Enquiry with, so far as one can tell, an identical mean- ing. No doubt this reflects changing intellectual fashions” (Miller, 1976, p. 161). Miller argues that Hume modified his ideas on justice and public interest in his second Enquiry. Miller criticizes Hume for interrupting relations with justice and ethics: Hume “justified the existence of rules of justice in terms of their utility, and refused to see justice as an independent moral value” (1976, p. 170). It seems that Miller is right in condemning opinions of Hume in this topic, because the measure of justice becomes utility. The source of justice loses its moral autonomy. The value of justice is determined by public utility now. This interpretation can be inferred evidently from the beginning part of section three of the second Enquiry: Justice is useful to society, and consequently that part of its merit, at least, must arise from that consideration, it would be a superfluous undertaking to prove. That public utility is the sole origin of justice, and that reflections on the beneficial consequences of this virtue are the sole foundation of its merit; this proposition, being more curious and important, will better deserve our examination and enquiry (Hume, 1998, p. 13). reasons for action or judgment which could derive from our particular, fluctuating, circumstance-gov- erned desires emotions and interests. Later on Adam Smith was to invoke sympathy for precisely the same purpose. But the gap of course is logically unbridgable, and ‘sympathy’ as used by Hume and Smith is the name of a philosophical fiction” (MacIntyre, 1984, p. 49). Enes Eryılmaz, David Hume’s Account of Justice 9 Finally, it is apparent that Hume sees public utility as the foundation of the value of justice. He puts off the principle of sympathy to ground just actions. In his later work, Hume gives emphasis to public utility for the virtue of justice. Yet public utility could not solve the problem of free rider either. The free rider utilizes from the beneficial consequences of the rules of justice, but she herself does not obey the rules. How will Hume or Nuyen convince the free rider? Why should she act ac- cording to the rules of justice? Since everyone except she obeys the rules of justice, social and economic life goes on. There is not a total defect in the system and public order is preserved. Which motive will force the free rider to comply with the laws of justice? The public utility argument could not persuade the free rider too. Circumstances of Justice To delineate the concept of justice then Hume presents some hypothetical condi- tions. In a sense, he offers thought experiments. In this way, Hume shows where and when we need justice. Throughout his investigation, he has recourse to nega- tive arguments in locating the notion of justice. Hume demonstrates where and when people do not and should not take into consideration the laws of justice. The essential requirements of justice then become visible. For Hume, therefore, it should first be understood where the laws of justice do not work. There are some conditions, communities, and beings for which the rules of justice become useless. Hume enumerates these exceptional states in the third section of the second Enqui- ry. To Hume, we do not need the idea of justice in these cases: 1. Unlimited abundance of needs 2. Extensive benevolence of man 3. Shortage of all basic needs 4. Perfect greed and malice of a society 5. State of emergency and war 6. Punishment of criminals 7. A class of rational creatures with mental and physical disabilities 8. Animals These cases show where justice becomes useless. Counter situations thus indi- cate required states of justice. So, these circumstances lead to the virtue of justice. Hume goes on to say that “there are some virtues, that produce pleasure and appro- bation by means of an artifice or contrivance, which arises from the circumstances and necessity of mankind. Of this kind I assert justice to be” (Hume, 1978, p. 477). Now, let us try to see these conditions of justice one by one. insan & toplum 10 The first imaginary situation is a place where there is a profusion of every type of needs and facilities. Anybody can obtain whatever she or he wants in large quan- tities. There is no need to argue and fight for any object in this prosperous state. Hume describes this condition as follows: Let us suppose that nature has bestowed on the human race such profuse abundance of all external conveniencies, that, without any uncertainty in the event, without any care or industry on our part, every individual finds himself fully provided with whatever his most voracious appetites can want, or luxurious imagination wish or desire. His natural beauty, we shall suppose, surpasses all acquired ornaments: The perpetual clemency of the seasons renders useless all clothes or covering: The raw herbage affords him the most delicious fare; the clear fountain, the richest beverage. No laborious occupation required: no tillage: no navigation. Music, poetry, and contemplation form his sole bu- siness: conversation, mirth, and friendship his sole amusement (Hume, 1998, p. 13). Hume concludes that the virtue of justice would be pointless in such a state. Since dispute and aggression will not occur in a satisfactory state, people do not require justice and equity: “in such a happy state, every other social virtue would flourish, and receive tenfold increase; but the cautious, jealous virtue of justice would never once have been dreamed of ” (Hume, 1998, p. 13; italics mine). In this circumstance, unlimited abundance of needs annihilates the jealous virtue of justice. Hume draws a relation between the virtue of justice and jealousy: we dis- cover that in this happy state there would be no jealousy. Given that in the perfect “welfare state” there is nothing to quarrel for, it is impossible to be jealous. So, if there is no jealousy, there is no disagreement. If there is no disagreement, there is no need for the virtue of justice. Hume contends that jealousy of advantage is an assumption of justice: “if nature supplied abundantly all our wants and desires, that the jealousy of interest, which justice supposes, could no longer have place” (1978, p. 494). Jealous virtue of justice therefore presumes jealousy of benefit. We cannot conceive of justice unless there is some jealousy of interest. Since extreme abundance does not permit jealousy of others’ objects and possessions, justice becomes entirely impractical. Hume supports his ideas at that point by means of questions, such as “[f]or what purpose make a partition of goods, where every one has already more than enough? Why give rise to property, where there cannot pos- sibly be any injury?” (Hume, 1978, p. 13). Why should anyone insist on mine and thine? The rules of justice and property would be unnecessary in this ideal state. Hume concludes that: “justice, in that case, being totally USELESS, would be an idle ceremonial, and could never possibly have place in the catalogue of virtues” (Hume, 1998, p. 13). Enes Eryılmaz, David Hume’s Account of Justice 11 The second thought experiment of Hume is an ideal fraternity where human beings are extremely benevolent to each other.11 Man considers interests of others rather than their subjective good. In case of extensive generosity justice becomes useless: “[e]ncrease to a sufficient degree the benevolence of men, or the bounty of nature, and you render justice useless, by supplying its place with much nobler vir- tues, and more valuable blessings” (Hume, 1978, pp. 494-495). For instance, when a son asks for a considerable amount of money from his father, the father gives the required amount and does not make a written agreement. The rules of justice are not necessary between a father and a son. Hypothetically, this is a family relation between the members of the society which is extremely benevolent: Why raise land-marks between my neighbour’s field and mine, when my heart has made no division between our interests; but shares all his joys and sorrows with the same force and vivacity as if originally my own? Every man, upon this supposition, being a second self to another, would trust all his interests to the discretion of every man; without jealousy, without partition, without distinction. And the whole human race would form only one family; where all would lie in common, and be used freely, without regard to property; but cautiously too, with as entire regard to the necessities of each individual, as if our own interests were most intimately concerned (Hume, 1998, p. 14). In such a state, each person is a supernatural being. Individuals treat each other as if they live in a big family; nobody is “other,” or “alien.” The principle of humanity is endorsed by the entire community. As they are close friends, they do not distinguish their commodities and facilities; “a cordial affection renders all things common among friends” (Hume, 1978, p. 495).12 They use their goods with others without hesitation. Likewise, “married people in particular mutually lose their property, and are unacquainted with the mine and thine, which are so necessary” (Hume, 1978, p. 495). Until couples are divorced, their properties and goods are considered together. Hume generalizes these specific cases and says that “if every one had the same affection and tender regard for every one as for himself; justice and injustice would be equally unknown among mankind” (Hume, 1978, p. 495). 11 It is apparent that circumstances and dispositions are very significant in the prerequisites of justice. There is a parallel between the conditions of justice and human beings. Hume also emphasizes situa- tions and tempers in the actions of men. 12 This idea reminds Aristotle’s famous statement in Nicomachean Ethics: “when people are friends, they have no need of justice” (Aristotle, 2011, Book 8, 1155a27). insan & toplum 12 In the following two conditions, David Hume conceives of opposite situations and imagines a place where there is a shortage of all vital requirements: a severe scarcity of basic needs. Again, the laws of justice are in limbo for a period when cir- cumstances become normal. In this state, “[g]rievous shortage would wreck laws of justice;” (Hardin, 2007, p. 141) similarly the rules of justice would be suspended in a disaster too. Catastrophic disasters demand emergency operations and the virtue of justice can be an obstacle in a state of necessity. Hume describes this atmosphere as follows: Suppose a society to fall into such want of all common necessaries, that the utmost fru- gality and industry cannot preserve the greater number from perishing, and the whole from extreme misery; it will readily, I believe, be admitted, that the strict laws of justice are suspended, in such a pressing emergence, and give place to the stronger motives of necessity and self-preservation. Is it any crime, after a shipwreck, to seize whatever means or instrument of safety one can lay hold of, without regard to former limitations of pro- perty? Or if a city besieged were perishing with hunger; can we imagine, that men will see any means of preservation before them, and lose their lives, from a scrupulous regard to what, in other situations, would be the rules of equity and justice? (Hume, 1998, p. 15). Obviously, people will try to survive in that condition. Since, “[t]he USE and TENDENCY of that virtue is to procure happiness and security, by preserving or- der in society,” (Hume, 1998, p. 15) justice can be ignored in excessive famine and wants. Prudence takes the role; the common people does not consider the princi- ples of justice in such a situation. For example, a hopeless person about to die of hunger should not be punished because of stealing something to eat. In the same way, “[t]he public, even in less urgent necessities, opens granaries, without the consent of proprietors; as justly supposing, that the authority of magistracy may, consistent with equity, extend so far…” (Hume, 1998, p. 15). Thus, the virtue of justice is of no use again. In the fourth hypothetical state, Hume imagines a society which is governed by perfect greed and malice. This is the state of nature as described by Thomas Hobbes in Leviathan (1994),13 but I think it is best portrayed in William Golding’s novel Lord of the Flies (1962). David Hume gives a picture of this savage condition in the second Enquiry: 13 Hume also refuses to see Thomas Hobbes as the first philosopher who conceives of the state of nature and argues that it can be found in the works of Cicero and Plato as well. For the details see second Enquiry (Hume, 1998, p. 17). Enes Eryılmaz, David Hume’s Account of Justice 13 Suppose likewise, that it should be a virtuous man’s fate to fall into the society of ruffi- ans, remote from the protection of laws and government; what conduct must he emb- race in that melancholy situation? He sees such a desperate rapaciousness prevail; such a disregard to equity, such contempt of order, such stupid blindness to future consequ- ences, as must immediately have the most tragical conclusion, and must terminate in destruction to the greater number, and in a total dissolution of society to the rest. He, meanwhile, can have no other expedient than to arm himself, to whomever the sword he seizes, or the buckler, may belong: To make provision of all means of defence and security (Hume, 1998, pp. 15-16). A man has no choice in those terms. From Hume’s point of view, behaving in accordance with the society is so natural. When the public is barbarous, you become brutal as well. When a state wage war with an uncivilized community “who observed no rules even of war, the former must also suspend their observance of them, where they no longer serve to any purpose; and must render every action or rencounter as bloody and pernicious as possible to the first aggressors” (Hume, 1998, p. 16). One suspends principles of justice and humanity in this situation. Hence, in this state of affairs, a man’s “particular regard to justice being no longer of use to his own safety or that of others, he must consult the dictates of self-preservation alone, without concern for those who no longer merit his care and attention” (Hume, 1998, p. 16). Consequently, the state of necessity trumps the laws of justice and equity. In Hume’s view, the fifth set of condition is the state of war and emergency. In those circumstances, the virtue of justice is adjourned until the end of warfare or emergency. First, Hume asserts that state of war dictates exceptional laws: “the rage and violence of public war; what is it but a suspension of justice among the warring parties, who perceive, that this virtue is now no longer of any use or advantage to them?” (Hume, 1998, p. 16). To Hume, an administration should defer the rules of justice in case of war. Second, a state of emergency causes interruption of justice as well. Hume argues that “the rules of justice may be dispensed with in cases of urgent necessity” (“Of Passive Obedience,” 1994, p. 203). Hume justifies suspension of the laws of justice in necessary situations. He grounds his argument in public utility: As the obligation to justice is founded entirely on the interests of society, which requ- ire mutual abstinence from property, in order to preserve peace among mankind; it is evident, that, when the execution of justice would be attained with very pernicious consequences, that virtue must be suspended, and give place to public utility, in such extraordinary and such pressing emergencies. The maxim, fiat Justitia & ruat Coelum, let justice be performed, though the universe be destroyed, it apparently false, and by sacrificing the end to the means, shews a preposterous idea of the subordination of duties (“Of Passive Obedience,” 1994, p. 202). insan & toplum 14 Hume employs one more exception in the adherence of the laws of justice: a state of emergency and necessity makes exceptions to justice.14 Hume gives this privilege to the sovereign state for the sake of raison d’etat: “[a]ll politicians will allow, and most philosophers, that REASONS of STATE may, in particular emer- gencies, dispense with the rules of justice, and invalidate any treaty or alliance, where the strict observance of it would be prejudicial” (Hume, 1998, p. 29). Fur- ther, Hume supports this authoritarian supremacy with the delay of the laws of justice in his ideal commonwealth: “[t]he protector, the two secretaries, the coun- cil of state, with any five or more that the senate appoints, are possessed, on ex- traordinary emergencies, of dictatorial power for six months” (“Idea of a Perfect Commonwealth,” 1994, p. 227). However, the problem is once the ruler seizes this supreme power, why should she leave this position and its prerogatives? One can easily prolong this period; as a matter of fact, states of exceptions are usually ex- tended arbitrarily in history. So, shelving laws of justice is an ambiguous and open practice.15 Hume’s sixth exception concerns punishment of public criminals. He recom- mends that persons who harm public order should be penalized according to their “own laws.” For Hume, this is the best way to discipline public criminals. Hence, the laws of justice may be forgotten once again. He explains the postponement of justice in the second Enquiry: When any man, even in political society, renders himself by his crimes, obnoxious to the public, he is punished by the laws in his goods and person; that is, the ordinary rules of justice are, with regard to him, suspended for a moment, and it becomes equitable to inflict on him, for the benefit of society, what otherwise he could not suffer without wrong or injury (Hume, 1998, p. 16). Public utility justifies this exception once more. Rules of justice happen to be futile again to maintain the order of society. The seventh thought experiment is about an imaginary class of rational crea- tures who have mental and physical disabilities. A vulnerable group of people should be treated with the principle of humanity rather than the principle of justice. It 14 Hume’s ideas on the state of emergency and necessity run through the minds Giorgio Agamben’s state of exception if the laws of justice are considered as law. Agamben, however, rejects “suspension of law” in the state of exception. For Agamben’s state of exception see Agamben, 2005, pp. 1-4. 15 For instance, “from a juridical standpoint the entire Third Reich can be considered a state of exception that lasted twelve years” (Agamben, 2005, p. 2). Enes Eryılmaz, David Hume’s Account of Justice 15 seems that these helpless people may be taken as psychologically ill or handicapped in need of nursing. To Hume, benevolence precedes justice in such a situation: Were there a species of creatures intermingled with men, which, though rational, were possessed of such inferior strength, both of body and mind, that they were incapable of all resistance, and could never, upon the highest provocation, make us feel the effects of their resentment; the necessary consequence, I think, is that we should be bound by the laws of humanity to give gentle usage to these creatures, but should not, properly speaking, lie under any restraint of justice with regard to them, nor could they possess any right or property, exclusive of such arbitrary lords (Hume, 1998, p. 18). In that condition, suspension of rules of justice may be acceptable, but Hume holds this inequality as good: “[o]ur intercourse with them could not be called so- ciety, which supposes a degree of equality; but absolute command on the one side, and servile obedience on the other” (Hume, 1998, p. 18). These independent per- sons control themselves if they wish, but they do not cross the line because of tenderness and benevolence. Therefore, “as no inconvenience ever results from the exercise of a power, so firmly established in nature, the restraints of justice and property, being totally useless, would never have place in so unequal a confederacy” (Hume, 1998, p. 18). Rules of justice suspended in this case as well. Finally, Hume says that relations of human beings with a class of rational crea- tures who have psychological and bodily disabilities (the former group) bear the same resemblance to their relations with animals: mankind has superiority over animals (Hume, 1998, p. 18).16 Rules of justice do not work before the animals too. Man behaves towards animals in accordance with benevolence and compassion. For Hume, the laws of justice cannot be employed for animals. Hence, in certain conditions compliance with the rules of justice become worthless, in others it is against public utility, and in some cases, it is at odds with the principle of humanity. In his investigation, Hume first establishes where justice is futile and pernicious in the circumstances and says that justice is necessary ex- cept these conditions. Hume discusses the subject in a similar way in the Treatise: 16 Meanwhile, Hume, having made an analogy between helpless people and animals, he also observes the relations of power between the American Indians and the “civilized Europeans” in the same fashion. He confesses that Europeans suspended principles of justice and humanity in America: “[t]he great su- periority of civilized EUROPEANS above barbarous INDIANS, tempted us to imagine ourselves on the same footing with regard to them, and made us throw off all restraints of justice, and even of humanity, in our treatment of them” (Hume, 1998, p. 18). insan & toplum 16 ‘tis evident, that the only cause, why the extensive generosity of man, and the perfect abundance of every thing, wou’d destroy the very idea of justice, is because they render it useless; and that, on the other hand, his confin’d benevolence, and his necessitous condition, give rise to that virtue, only by making it requisite to the publick interest, and to that of every individual. (Hume, 1978, p. 496). If extensive generosity of men does not permit the rise of justice, then limited generosity can provide it. If extreme abundance and shortage makes justice point- less, then some degree of requirements makes justice possible. Hume’s negative approach to the laws of justice is apparent in the second Enquiry as well: Thus, the rules of equity or justice depend entirely on the particular state and condition in which men are placed, and owe their origin and existence to that UTILITY, which re- sults to the public from their strict and regular observance. Reverse, in any considerable circumstance, the condition of men: Produce extreme abundance or extreme necessity: Implant in the human breast perfect moderation and humanity, or perfect rapacious- ness and malice: By rendering justice totally useless, you thereby totally destroy its es- sence, and suspend its obligation upon mankind. (Hume, 1998, p. 16). Although Hume has a negative attitude in his analysis, he nevertheless wishes a society which is compatible with the rules of justice. He aspires to find the exact place of the idea of justice, and he follows the principle of utility in this pursuit. Besides, Hume’s arguments about conditions of justice point out that the vir- tue of justice should be considered in its background. A just person comes into existence in a community. For Hume, the moral subject is in conformity with the society and circumstances. There is no tension between the society and the individ- ual. If there are circumstances to be just, one can behave justly; if not, one does not act justly. There is no distinction between the empirical and the intelligible realm in Hume’s theory of justice. The “moral subject” adheres to the community in which she exists. Circumstantial and empirical environment is notoriously important in the observance of the rules of justice. So, if one lives in a society that is not just, then one acts unjustly too. If one lives in a group of people who are just because of their interests and public utility, then one becomes a just individual too. The reverse is not true. If a society is constituted by immoral persons, you do not have to be just. Circumstances and human beings are therefore very significant in de- termining justice. To Hardin, Hume “shows that we cannot sensibly have a theory of justice that is not contingent on human nature and the conditions that humans face in their world” (Hardin, 2007, p. 140). So, it appears that there is no idea of justice regardless of interests in Hume. Unlike Plato, there is not a world of ideas Enes Eryılmaz, David Hume’s Account of Justice 17 in which justice exists. In Hume’s view, the virtue of justice is in the sensible world and it is related with the human condition. Despite John Rawls’ entire approval of Hume’s circumstances of justice,17 the Humean conception of justice is unlike the Rawlsian; because the Rawlsian theory of justice is abstract and ideal, whereas Hume’s notion of justice is concerned with normal conditions. Hardin draws our attention to this point: “Hume demonstrates that any notion of justice we might be committed to cannot simply be abstract or inferred entirely from reason or ideal- ized circumstances” (2007, p. 140). It is obvious that Hume’s anti-rationalistic atti- tude can be seen in his conception of justice. Hardin underlines this point: “Hume’s empiricism and naturalism (and by his lights his Newtonian stance) on these fac- tors are forcefully represented by his discussion of the empirical circumstances of justice” (2007, p. 139). Dependence of justice on human and social conditions evi- dently indicates Hume’s empirical methodology.18 Artificial Virtue of Justice Hume seeks out motivations behind actions in determining virtue and vice; so, in Part II of Book III of the Treatise, he inspects motives behind just actions. Hume cannot find any natural motive behind just actions. Accordingly, he concludes that “the sense of justice and injustice is not derived from nature, but arises artificial- ly, though necessarily from education, and human conventions” (Hume, 1978, p. 483). Conditions and necessities of nature compel men to establish rules of jus- tice. Hence, convention and education foster the sense of justice. For Hume, we need justice because of the troubles in human nature and society, such as self-love, limited generosity, and scarcity of goods (Hume, 1978, p. 495). These deficiencies cannot be removed by natural ways. Hume emphasizes this fact in the Treatise: In vain shou’d we expect to find, in uncultivated nature, a remedy to this inconvenience; or hope for any inartificial principle of the human mind, which might controul those partial affections, and make us overcome the temptations arising from our circumstan- ces (Hume, 1978, p. 488). 17 “Now this constellation of conditions I shall refer to as the circumstances of justice. Hume’s account of them is especially perspicuous and the preceding summary adds nothing essential to his much fuller discussion” (Rawls, 1999, p. 110). 18 This conclusion forces us to see Alasdair MacIntyre as right concerning the is/ought question and juss- tice: “Hume himself derives “ought” from “is” in his account of justice” (MacIntyre, 1959, p. 459). insan & toplum 18 Hence, to Hume, human conventions and artifices19 can bring relief to these problems. What does human convention mean? What is the characteristic of a con- vention? Is it a contract, a treaty or a promise? Hume mentions the following ideas regarding these questions: This convention is not of the nature of a promise: For even promises themselves, as we shall see afterwards, arise from human conventions. It is only a general sense of com- mon interest; which sense all the members of the society express to one another, and which induces them to regulate their conduct by certain rules. I observe, that it will be for my interest to leave another in the possession of his goods, provided he will act in the same manner with regard to me. He is sensible of a like interest in the regulation of his conduct. When this common sense of interest is mutually expressed, and is known to both, it produces a suitable resolution and behaviour. And this may properly enou- gh be call’d a convention or agreement betwixt us, tho’ without the interposition of a promise; since the actions of each of us have a reference to those of the other, and are perform’d upon the supposition, that something is to be perform’d on the other part (Hume, 1978, p. 490). So, convention is neither a compact20 nor a promise. Convention is a sensation of public interest that arranges actions of people. In the second Enquiry, Hume re- lates human conventions with “public utility” (Hume, 1998, p. 98).21 In the Treatise he explains conventions by referring to values of gold and silver: “[i]n like manner do gold and silver become the common measures of exchange, and are esteemed sufficient payment for what is of a hundred times their value” (Hume, 1978, p. 490). The same is true for the money we use: if individuals did not accept money as a measure of value and use it as everyone does, it would be a piece of paper. Human convention adds value to money. Let us now consider Hume’s distinction between natural and artificial virtues. The difference between natural and artificial virtues becomes visible when the con- 19 To Hume, artifice means that “the rules of justice were invented by human beings in the course of their natural history and thus cannot be considered original, or as innate principles made known to men by nature’s Author” (Lecaldano, 2008, p. 258). 20 Macnabb underlines this view in Hume: “The principles of justice are, indeed, founded on artifices, and are therefore not “natural laws”. But they are not founded on any contract, since the keeping of contracts is itself one of the principles of justice. They are founded on customary conventions which command our approbation because of their utility” (Macnabb, 1991, p. 171). 21 “[I]f by convention be meant a sense of common interest; which sense each man feels in his own breast, which he remarks in his fellows, and which carries him, in concurrence with others, into a general plan or system of actions, which tends to public utility; it must be owned, that, in this sense, justice arises from human conventions” (Hume, 1998, p. 98). Enes Eryılmaz, David Hume’s Account of Justice 19 sequences are considered. For instance, benevolence is a natural virtue and justice an artificial one; Hume associates benevolence with a wall, and justice with a vault: The happiness and prosperity of mankind, arising from the social virtue of benevolence and its subdivisions, may be compared to a wall, built by many hands, which still rises by each stone that is heaped upon it, and receives increase proportional to the diligence and care of each workman. The same happiness, raised by the social virtue of justice and its subdivisions, may be compared to the building of a vault, where each individual stone would, of itself, fall to the ground; nor is the whole fabric supported but by the mutual assistance and combination of its corresponding parts (Hume, 1998, p. 97). This striking illustration shows the distinction between justice and benevo- lence clearly, or the one between artificial virtues and natural virtues. Therefore, if a just society is dreamed of, all human beings should obey the laws of justice completely. This is also the ground of inflexible laws that Hume advocates. In- flexible laws can be secured when every single person sticks to them. When the social virtue of justice is endorsed in this manner, it can be satisfied; otherwise the vault would be demolished. In artificial virtues, all people should comply with plans and rules of conduct. This is the critical point in the distinction between natural and artificial virtues. Hume confirms and elaborates this distinction in the Treatise: The only difference betwixt the natural virtues and justice lies in this, that the good, which results from the former, arises from every single act, and is the object of some natural passion: Whereas a single act of justice, consider’d in itself, may often be cont- rary to the public good; and ‘tis only the concurrence of mankind, in a general scheme or system of action, which is advantageous. When I relieve persons in distress, my natural humanity is my motive; and so far as my succour extends, so far have I promoted the happiness of my fellow-creatures. But if we examine all the questions, that come before any tribunal of justice, we shall find, that, considering each case apart, it wou’d as often be an instance of humanity to decide contrary to the laws of justice as conformable them (Hume, 1978, p. 579). General rules of justice (artificial virtues) thus should not be examined sepa- rately. The important thing is “[t]he whole scheme … of law and justice is advanta- geous to the society; and it was with a view to this advantage, that men, by their voluntary conventions, established it” (Hume, 1978, p. 579). However, in large so- cieties free riders can elude their responsibilities ingeniously. They do not destroy the entire system. Free riders pursue their interests without abolishing the system of laws directly. Of course, if every citizen acts like that, the system collapses. In practice, governments seek to prevent free riders with penalties, but Hume does insan & toplum 20 not refer to legal or financial sanctions (Nuyen, 1986, p. 53). So, how will he deter free riders and make them respect the laws of justice? Since justice is an artficial virtue, there is not any natural motive that forces people to abide by the laws. So how will Hume bridge the gap morally? Why should free riders obey the rules of justice? Why should they leave this advantaged position? Unfortunately, Hume could not answer this questions. He just mentions benefits of justice, but he could not find a solid moral basis for just actions. Hume expresses that artificial virtues should be performed by all, but he could not explain how it is possible. In addition to that Hume speaks of law and justice together. He says that both are beneficial to the public. Since law and justice are compatible in Hume’s political thought, we can say that justice can be achieved and preserved by law. Then, the laws of justice are needed for ordering human conduct in the society. The Laws of Justice In Hume’s works, we encounter concepts such as “rules of justice” (Hume, 1978, p. 480), “laws of nature” (Hume, 1978, p. 520), “laws of society” (Hume, 1978, p. 491), “fundamental laws of nature” (Hume, 1978, p. 526), “fundamental rules of justice” (Hume, 1978, p. 567), “rules of justice and equity” (Hume, 1978, p. 505), “laws of equity and justice” (Hume, 1998, p. 28), “laws of justice” (Hume, 1978, p. 491), and “laws of justice and of property” (Hume, 1998, p. 23). In fact, these con- ceptualizations refer to same principles, which are as follows: 1. Stability of property; 2. Transfer of property by consent; 3. Fulfilment of promises (Hume, 1978, p. 526). Hume elucidates the first law of nature as follows: “man’s property is suppos’d to be fenc’d against every mortal, in every possible case” (Hume, 1978, p. 483). Hume sees the right to property as an absolute right. He subsequently draws a parallel between property and justice: After this convention, concerning abstinence from the possessions of others, is enter’d into, and every one has acquir’d a stability in his possessions, there immediately arise the ideas of justice and injustice; as also those of property, right, and obligation. The lat- ter are altogether unintelligible without first understanding the former. Our property is, nothing but those goods, whose constant possession is established by the laws of society; that is, by the laws of justice (Hume, 1978, pp. 490-491). Enes Eryılmaz, David Hume’s Account of Justice 21 Humean rules of justice are very much related with the rules of property. This is also apparent from his frequent use of these notions together. For instance, in the second Enquiry Hume says that “the ultimate point … is the interest and hap- piness of human society. Where this enters not into consideration, nothing can appear more whimsical, unnatural, and even superstitious, than all or most of the laws of justice and of property” (Hume, 1998, p. 23; emphasis added). In his Political Essays, Hume admits that “private justice, or the abstinence from the properties of others, is a most cardinal virtue” (“Of the Original Contract,” 1994, p. 197). In the second Enquiry, he uses justice and property interchangeably (Hume, 1998, p. 19). It is evident that Humean laws of justice are in line with the rules of property.22 As John Rawls observes, “Hume’s principles of justice are, in effect, largely principles for the regulation of economic production and competition between the members of civil society, as they pursue their economic interests” (Rawls, 2007, pp. 178- 179). Hence, Hume’s rules of justice are mostly principles of economic activities; because the rules of justice derive from the rules of property, and these rules seek to regulate economic transactions. For Hume, since all the three rules of justice is related to property and economics, the laws of justice are the laws of finance and commerce (Wennerlind, 2002). Self-love At first sight, self-interest seems to be in contrast with the laws of justice; however, for Hume, self-love is the original motive for the rules of justice. To underline this nuance, let us first consider rough and brutal self-interest. In the Treatise, Hume states that “self-love, when it acts at its liberty, instead of engaging us to honest 22 David Gauthier confirms this interpretation; he says that in Hume’s view “property is determined by a system of rules for the possession and use of objects, so that my property is what, in accordance with rules, I possess and use, and my exclusive property, what I alone possess and use. Justice, then, is the virtue determined by such a system, so that just behaviour consists in adherence to the rules governing the possession and use of objects” (Gauthier, 1979, pp. 4-5). Furthermore, Alasdair Mac- Intyre observes Humean conception of justice as rules of property as well: “[t]he problem of justice was according to Hume centrally a problem about the rules of property and their enforcement, and as I have already suggested, it was property conceived of in one highly particular way” (MacIntyre, 1988, p. 307). Similarly, Charles Cottle understands Hume’s notion of justice in accordance with the notion of prop- erty; “because Hume’s conception of property depends upon the laws which regulate it, one who wishes to hold, acquire, transfer, or even respect property must abide by such rules of justice. For Hume it is definitionally impossible to violate the rules of justice and still respect property rights. Semantically, the rules of justice and property are inseparable” (Cottle, 1979, p. 460). A. T. Nuyen thinks so as well: “Justice, for Hume, is observation of the rules designed to promote the stability of property.… Justice, for Hume, has to do only with material possessions.” (Nuyen, 1986, p. 43). insan & toplum 22 actions, is the source of all injustice and violence; nor can a man ever correct those vices, without correcting and restraining the natural movements of that appetite” (Hume, 1978, p. 480). Hence, self-interest should be controlled; otherwise it is im- possible to satisfy the desires of self-love. No one can be satisfied in his or her interests. At that point, persons should control their self-love just because of their self-interest.23 The obstacle of self-love is thus transformed to become the first or- igin of justice. Hume contends that “the mutual shocks, in society, and the oppo- sitions of interest and self-love have constrained mankind to establish the laws of justice, in order to preserve the advantages of mutual assistance and protection” (Hume, 1998, p. 67). Hence, for Hume, the motivation of the laws of justice comes from the domestication of self-love: We have already shewn, that men invented the three fundamental laws of nature, when they observed the necessity of society to their mutual subsistance, and found, that it was impossible to maintain any correspondence together, without some restraint on their natural appetites. The same self-love, therefore, which renders men so incommo- dious to each other, taking a new and more convenient direction, produces the rules of justice, and is the first motive of their observance (Hume, 1978, p. 543). Self-interest so tamed becomes the first origin of justice. For Hume, therefore, individuals obey the laws of justice. In other words, “artificially-redirected interest naturally obliges us and serves as the original motive to justice” (Taylor, 1998, p. 19) or “enlightened self-interest” (Krause, 2004, p. 639) motivates us to obey the laws of justice. It may be argued that Hume denies self-love as a foundation of morality. In- deed, Hume rejects selfishness as a basis in ethics, but he acknowledges the role of self-interest in politics. This distinction is observed by Jeffrey Church. He argues that “[a]lthough Hume began his moral philosophy with a critique of the selfish system, he returns to the selfish hypothesis in his political philosophy” (Church, 2007, p. 174). As I have noted above, this can be seen in Hume’s arguments on justice. In this question, Hume stands between Hutcheson and Mandeville. Hume is not in agreement with Hutcheson with respect to the self-interest: “[u]nlike his predecessor Hutcheson, who thoroughly repudiated the selfish system, Hume re- mained ambivalent about it, accepting its institutional solutions while rejecting its 23 A relation could be drawn between this remark of Hume and Game Theory. John Nash introduced this original approach to Game Theory. In zero sum games, one’s profit is others’ deficit, but in non-zero sum games all sides of the competition can win. Everyone can satisfy their interests. This can be also named as restriction of self-love in Hume. Nash formulates this idea in economic terms. See Nash, 1950. Enes Eryılmaz, David Hume’s Account of Justice 23 moral assumptions” (Church, 2007, p. 179). Hume “seems to accept Mandeville’s system in the end” (Church, 2007, p. 174), but only in the political realm. However, MacIntyre claims that grounding the rules of justice on self-love is unsatisfactory: “the kind of connection between the passions and adherence to a rule or princi- ple, which the Humean account requires, cannot be established by way of any con- ception of self-interest” (MacIntyre, 1988, p. 307). To Sharon Krause, Hume’s ap- proach to justice is related with interests; “defining justice as narrowly as he does, Hume means to force a change in our orientation to justice, to make us feel for justice from the standpoint of our interests rather than our ideals” (Krause, 2004, p. 639). Idealistic discourses thus leave their place to egoistic discourses in the the- ory of justice. However, Hume’s approach could not remedy the free rider problem. The free rider does not control and redirect her self-love. Hume suggests that she should restrict her self-love for the sake of self-love. This argument looks like a vicious circle. The cunning free rider satisfies her self-love anyway. Why would she limit her self-love? Hume needs another reason to curb self-love and to arrive at the rules of justice. Self-love is not a sure foundation in ethics as well as in politics. Self-love could not serve just and moral actions. The Origin of the State In his philosophical and political texts, Hume prefers the notion of government rather than state, but this does not mean that he refers to a different apparatus. In general, Hume implies state when he uses the term government. In fact, the term government was not employed as we understand and perceive it now. To- day, as a rule the government is responsible for executive and legislative powers. However, in Hume’s theory, the term government includes judicial power as well (Dees, 2008, p. 396). To be brief, in Hume, the term government has a larger sense than its contemporary meaning. Therefore, we can use government and state inter- changeably in our investigation of the rules of justice. An anarchist can ask why we need a state. Cannot we live without government? Hume would consider this question as important to some extent. Considering American clans, he argues that the state is superfluous in small societies (Hume, 1978, p. 540); but in a large and developed society an authority is necessary to guarantee the laws of justice. Hence, people “establish government, as a new in- vention to attain their ends, and preserve the old, or procure new advantages, by a more strict execution of justice” (Hume, 1978, p. 543). Thanks to the state, the public will obey the laws of justice. Thus, “the principal object of government is to insan & toplum 24 constrain men to observe the laws of nature” (Hume, 1978, p. 543). Therefore, gov- ernments, parliaments, soldiers, officers are all needed for the sake of justice. On Hume’s view, therefore mankind needs an institution like the state: MAN, born in a family, is compelled to maintain society, from necessity, from natural inclination, and from habit. The same creature, in his farther progress, is engaged to establish political society, in order to administer justice; without which there can be no peace among them, nor safety, nor mutual intercourse. We are, therefore, to look upon all the vast apparatus of our government, as having ultimately no other object or purpose but the distribution of justice, or, in other words, the support of the twelve judges. Kings and parliaments, fleets and armies, officers of the court and revenue, am- bassadors, ministers, and privy-counsellors, are all subordinate in their end to this part of administration (“Of the Origin of Government,” 1994, p. 20). The artificial virtue of justice thus stands above all these organizations and in- dividuals. Political society functions as a controller and guardian. States are means to the ends of a just society; they guarantee the adherence to the rules of justice. Since human nature is inclined to self-interest, the government hinders people crossing the line. In the Political Essays, Hume underlines the purpose of state: All men are sensible of the necessity of justice to maintain peace and order; and all men are sensible of the necessity of peace and order for the maintenance of society. Yet, notwithstanding this strong and obvious necessity, such is the frailty or perverseness of our nature! It is impossible to keep men, faithfully and unerringly, in the paths of justice (“Of the Origin of Government,” 1994, p. 20). In Hume’s political thought, therefore, it can be said that states are just “useful tools” (Dees, 2008, p. 404). Governments should support the laws of justice for the well-being of the society. Conclusion In this paper, Hume’s theory of justice is examined in terms of its foundations, circumstances, and characteristics. Hume analyses justice by referring to sympathy first; but in his later works he leaves sympathy for the sake of public utility. He con- siders sympathy as a weak foundation for the virtue of justice. Then he emphasizes public utility for the moral approbation of justice. For Hume, the sense of justice does not originate from reason. His understanding of justice is not idealistic, abso- lute, and abstract; it is empirical and down-to-earth because he is concerned with interests rather than transcendental ideas. However, in Hume’s view, justice is a Enes Eryılmaz, David Hume’s Account of Justice 25 moral issue in large and refined societies. Obeying the laws of justice is a moral duty; hence, moral persons act in accordance with the principle of public utility. On the one hand, Hume could not overcome the free rider problem. Neither sym- pathy nor public utility could not supply the required ground work for justice. Free riders and sensible knaves can benefit from exceptions without violating general rules. Hume could not offer a remedy for free riders. Although Hume is a realist in politics, he seems like a Pollyanna in ethics. Hume’s account of justice could not provide a solution to the free rider problem that any theory of justice must deal with. On the other hand, Hume argues that justice is an artificial virtue and at the same time he contends that it is a moral duty and derives from a sense of obligation. But since justice does not involve a natural motive in human nature, a sense of obligation could not lead to justice. Although Hume adopts an empirical and anti-rationalist methodology, he appeals to rationalist solutions as well (Slote & LeBar, 2016). At the end of the day, Hume’s account of justice contains a set of gaps and contradictions. Therefore, he could not develop a complete well-grounded theory of justice (Reidy, 1993). For Hume, the virtue of justice becomes redundant in some situations, such as in states of perfect abundance, scarcity, war, and emergency. Similarly, when one is faced with perfectly generous, or extremely cruel and voracious persons, or when one is dealing with a class of rational creatures with mental and corporal disabili- ties, or with animals, or in the punishment of unlawful people, the virtue of justice would be pointless. In all other cases, the artificial virtue of justice plays an import- ant role. Circumstances and dispositions of men are thus highly important in the requirements of justice. This observation points to another resemblance between his theory of morality and justice, and helps us to see his experimental method of reasoning. As it is shown, Hume‘s empirical methodology is clear in his arguments concerning the circumstances of justice; but in the foundation of justice he implies rationalist concepts. To Hume, justice is an artificial virtue, it does not stem from nature, and it has not got a natural motive in human nature. The chief drive that causes individuals to act justly is disciplined self-interest. Self-love should be organized for needs of the public. Laws of justice are created by people thanks to the conventions. Civil society requires the rules of justice to institute and maintain order. With the rules of justice, the security and stability of the community is guaranteed. Unlike benef- icence or charity, justice necessitates participation of all people. The laws of justice should be followed by everybody; this is how a just society becomes possible. In insan & toplum 26 this way, well-being and maintenance of the society might be possible. If the virtue of justice is undermined, civil society collapses. Justice is a sine qua non for the hu- manity. Otherwise, brutality and anarchy overwhelm mankind. The laws of justice are mainly related to economic justice. In Hume’s political theory, the concept of justice chiefly concerns principles of economic activities; because he views the rules of justice from the lens of property. The laws of justice are: stability of property, exchange of property by consent, and performance of promises. The laws of justice are directly associated with the laws of property and exchange. Hume identifies the concept of justice with the rise of the first rule, i.e. stability of property. The other rules of justice too are concerned with property, trade, and contracts. Hume’s laws of justice are thus all about economics. References Agamben, G. (2005). State of exception (K. Attell, Trans.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Aristotle. (2011). Aristotle’s nicomachean ethics (R. C. Bartlett & S. D. Collins, Trans.). Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press. Church, J. (2007). Selfish and moral politics: David Hume on stability and cohesion in the modern state. The Journal of Politics, 69(1), 169-181. Cohon, R. (2010). Hume’s moral philosophy. (Fall Edition). In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2010/entries/hume-moral/ Cottle, C. E. (1979). Justice as artificial virtue in Hume’s treatise. Journal of the History of Ideas, 40, 457-466. Dees, R. H. (2008). “One of the finest and most subtile inventions”: Hume on government. In E. S. Radcliffe (Ed.), A companion to Hume (pp. 388-405). Oxford: Blackwell Publishing. Deleuze, G. (1991). Empiricism and subjectivity: An essay on Hume’s theory of human nature (C. V. Boundas, Trans.). New York: Columbia University Press. Eryılmaz, E. (2011). Politics, law, and morality: David Hume on justice. Unpublished master’s thesis, Middle East Tech- nical University, Ankara. Gauthier, D. (1979). David Hume, contractarian. The Philosophical Review, 88(1), 3-38. Golding, W. (1962). Lord of the flies. London: Faber & Faber. Haakonssen, K. (1993). The structure of Hume’s political theory. In D. F. Norton (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Hume (pp. 182-201). Cambridge : Cambridge University Press. Hardin, R. (2007). David Hume: Moral and political theorist. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hardin, R. (2013) The free rider problem. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2013 Ed.). Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2013/entries/free-rider/ Hobbes, T. (1994). Leviathan. E. Curley (Ed.). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company. Hume, D. (1978). A treatise of Human nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hume, D. (1994). Political essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hume, D. (1998). An enquiry concerning the principles of morals. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Krause, S. R. (2004). Hume and the (false) Luster of justice. Political Theory, 32(5), 628-655. Enes Eryılmaz, David Hume’s Account of Justice 27 Küng, H. (1998). A global ethic for global politics and economics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Lecaldano, E. (2008). Hume’s theory of justice, or artificial virtue. In E. S. Radcliffe (Ed.), A companion to Hume (pp. 257-272). Oxford: Blackwell Publishing. MacIntyre, A. (1959). Hume on “Is” and “Ought”. The Philosophical Review, 68(4), 451-468. MacIntyre, A. (1984). After virtue: A study in moral theory. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. MacIntyre, A. (1988). Whose justice? Which rationality? Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. Macnabb, D. G. (1991). David Hume: His theory of knowledge and morality. Aldershot, England: Gregg Revivals. Miller, D. (1976). Social justice. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Morwood, J. (1998). A dictionary of Latin words and phrases. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Nash, J. F. (1950). The bargaining problem. Econometrica, 18(2), 155-162. Nuyen, A. T. (1986). Hume’s justice as a collective good. Hume Studies, 12(1), 39-56. Rawls, J. (1999). A theory of justice (Rev. ed.). Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. Rawls, J. (2007). Lectures on the history of political philosophy. S. Freeman (Ed.). Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. Reidy, D. A. (1993). Does Hume have a theory of justice? Auslegung: A Journal of Philosophy, 19(1), 63-74. Selby-Bigge, L. A. (1975). Editor’s introduction. In D. Hume (Ed.), Enquiries concerning human understanding and concerning the principles of morals (p. xxi). Oxford: Clarendon Press. Slote, M., & LeBar, M. (2016). Justice as a virtue. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2016 Ed.). Retrieved from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/justice-virtue/ Taylor, J. (1998). Justice and the foundations of social morality in Hume’s treatise. Hume Studies, 24(1), 5-30. Wennerlind, C. (2002). David Hume’s political philosophy: A theory of commercial modernization. Hume Studies, 28(2), 247-270. Yellin, M. E. (2000). Indirect utility, justice, and equality in the political thought of David Hume. Critical Review, 14(4), 375-389. work_bbmjruecbrcfnfpc3v5ypzxsti ---- Microsoft Word - Gilabert--Justice and Beneficence (CRISPP).doc   1   “Justice and Beneficence” [Penultimate version; forthcoming in a special issue of Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy] Pablo Gilabert Philosophy Department, Concordia University, Montreal, Canada What is a duty of justice? And how is it different from a duty of beneficence? We need a clear account of the contrast. Unfortunately, there is no consensus in the philosophical literature as to how to characterize it. Different articulations of it have been provided, but it is hard to identify a common core that is invariant across them. In this paper, I propose an account of how to understand duties of justice, explain how it contrasts with several proposals as to how to distinguish justice and beneficence, respond to some objections and suggest further elaborations of it. The conceptual exploration pursued in this paper has practical stakes. A central aim is to propose and defend a capacious concept of justice that makes a direct discussion of important demands of justice (domestic and global) possible. Duties of justice can be positive besides negative, they can be imperfect as well as perfect, they can range over personal besides institutional contexts, they can include multiple associative reasons such us non-domination, non- exploitation and reciprocity, and they can even go beyond existing national, political, and economic associative frameworks to embrace strictly universal humanist concerns. We should reject ideological abridgments of the concept of justice that render these possibilities, and the important human interests and claims they may foster, invisible. 1. Introduction It is common to assume that there is an important distinction between justice and beneficence (or charity, humanitarianism—I treat them as equivalent here). This distinction between duties to others seems important, for example, when we think about our distributive responsibilities. Some believe that certain duties to help the needy or the relatively poor are duties of justice, whereas others claim that they are only duties of beneficence. Some believe that some of those duties are duties of justice in domestic, but not in global contexts. But what is a duty of justice? And how is it different from a duty of beneficence? We need a clear account of the contrast. Unfortunately, there is no consensus in the philosophical literature as to how to characterize it. Different articulations of it have been provided, but it is hard to identify a common core that is invariant across them. In this paper, I propose an account of how to understand duties of justice (section 2), explain how it contrasts with several proposals as to how to distinguish justice and beneficence   2   (section 3), and respond to some objections and suggest further elaborations of it (section 4). My focus will largely be on distributive justice (i.e. on the just apportioning of access to material goods and conditions affecting subsistence or well-being, including for example housing, health care, education, alimentation, opportunities for productive and meaningful work, income and wealth, instruments of production, and natural resources). The conceptual exploration pursued in this paper has practical stakes. A central aim is to propose and defend a capacious concept of justice that makes a direct discussion of important demands of justice (domestic and global) possible. Duties of justice can be positive besides negative, they can be imperfect as well as perfect, they can range over personal besides institutional contexts, they can include multiple associative reasons such as non-domination, non- exploitation and reciprocity, and they can even go beyond existing national, political, and economic associative frameworks to embrace strictly universal humanist concerns. We should reject ideological abridgments of the concept of justice that render these possibilities, and the important human interests and claims they may foster, invisible. 2. A proposal for how to understand duties of justice Let me start by presenting my view about how to understand duties of justice. I suggest that we conceive of them as follows: Duties of justice are duties to preserve or promote people’s access to important conditions or goods to which they are entitled and whose fulfillment is prima facie enforceable. This enforcement is all things considered justifiable if it is necessary for or strongly contributes to securing the required preservation or promotion and can be feasibly introduced without imposing unreasonable costs.   3   There are different ways to develop this concept into a more specific conception of justice.1 That development would involve providing substantive accounts answering questions such as the following: What conditions or goods are important enough to give rise to rights and duties of justice?2 What duties of preservation or promotion are reasonable to accept? What makes a proposed form of enforcement necessary for or strongly contributory to the fulfillment of a right? What considerations bear on the appraisal of the feasibility and reasonable costs of the enforcement of a duty? What areas of social life are amenable to demands of justice (i.e. what is justice’s site)? What are the criteria for identifying duty-bearers and right-holders (i.e. what is justice’s scope)? Different conceptions of justice can differ in their answers to these questions while sharing the concept as characterized above. They can agree on the role of justice in identifying prima facie enforceable duties to secure people’s rights even if they disagree about what makes duties fit for that role. I will explain these points further in section 3. But before proceeding let me say something about the status of my discussion. The account of the concept of duties of justice just provided is neither a stipulation nor an elucidation, but something in between these that we can call a deliberative interpretive proposal. A deliberative interpretive proposal shares with elucidation the interpretive interest in relating the account of a concept to the practices in which that concept may be used. But it differs from elucidation (and gets closer to stipulation) in that its core aim is deliberative rather than descriptive: it does not merely report what some agents in fact think, but makes a suggestion as to what they are to think. The aim is to propose an understanding of justice that relates to certain practices in which elements of the concept may be already in use, or where the concept may be relevant, while offering an articulation of the concept that may improve on the current concept or its understanding and thus help ameliorate the practice itself.   4   In proposing and defending the deliberative interpretive proposal mentioned, it is helpful to proceed by considering some reasonable desiderata, or adequacy conditions, for an account of duties of justice. What do we want to achieve by identifying some duties as duties of justice? What theoretical and practical work would a distinction between such duties and duties of beneficence do for us? The following are some of the desiderata I think worth recognizing (I do not claim that this list is exhaustive): (a) Capturing the stringency of justice. Justice involves demands that are very strong and that normally override competing considerations. An account of justice should pick out this feature. (b) Enabling rather than suppressing substantive debates. We should not propose an understanding of the concept of justice that is so narrow that it renders important substantive debates about duties of justice irrelevant. We want to engage intelligently in those debates and to reach a considered view about what position to support. Eliminating options by definitional fiat impoverishes our practical reasoning. (c) Determinateness. Our understanding of justice should be tolerably determinate. Ideally, we should identify necessary and sufficient conditions for the application of the concept of justice. Failing that, we should at least identify typical features holding for an important range of cases.3 (d) Capturing the critical role of justice. Conceptions of justice have a practical role in criticizing social practices and institutions. We should be suspicious of accounts of justice that do not help us make sense of challenges to the status quo. (e) Illuminating practices. Our account of the concept of justice should help us clarify the stakes of important practical questions.   5   3. How the proposed account relates to several proposals as to how to distinguish justice from beneficence The following are the main contrasts that have been proposed to identify the specificity of duties of justice: I. Due. Duties of justice, unlike duties of beneficence, are concerned with giving people their due. II. Negative / Positive. Duties of justice are negative, whereas duties of beneficence are positive (the former demand that we avoid depriving others of access to certain important conditions or goods, while the latter demand that we provide them with such an access or protect them when they already have it). III. Perfect / Imperfect. Duties of justice are perfect, whereas duties of beneficence are imperfect (the former are, and the latter are not, such that it is always clear who owes what to whom in what circumstances). IV. Enforceability. Duties of justice are justifiably enforceable, whereas duties of beneficence are not. V. Rights. Duties of justice have correlative rights, whereas duties of beneficence do not. VI. Institutional / Personal. Duties of justice are institutional, whereas duties of beneficence are interpersonal. VII. Associative / Non-associative. Duties of justice are always associative (they hold only amongst those who share a certain associative framework—such as a system of economic cooperation, a state, etc.), whereas duties of beneficence (sometimes) are not.4 The understanding of justice I proposed in section 2 combines some elements of contrasts I, IV, and V (although, as it will become clear, it does not collapse into any of them). On this understanding, duties of justice range over what is due to people. Just distribution is a response to   6   people’s rights to what is distributed. And distribution warrants enforcement. Such enforcement is seen as only prima facie warranted, however. Enforcement imposes constraints on the freedom of agents and involves burdens for them, and such costs must themselves be justifiable as feasible and reasonable. Hence, a duty could be a duty of justice even if a specific implementation of it is not justifiably enforceable, all things considered, in certain circumstances (either because in the circumstances such an enforcement is not feasible or because it imposes costs that are unreasonable given other, stronger, conflicting demands of justice). But since a pro tanto ground for action persists, agents may have to find alternative (feasible, reasonable) ways to honor it, or change the circumstances so that some form of honoring the ground becomes practicable. Consider, for example, the duty to help eradicate severe poverty. Access to basic nutrition, housing, education, and medical care constitute urgent interests that give rise to rights. The fulfillment of the correlative negative duty not to deprive others of access to basic necessities is clearly worthy of enforcement. So arguably is a positive duty to help others gain and maintain such an access. Now, the latter duty is clearly feasible at reasonable cost in most contemporary societies. It could be argued that this is not the case in extremely poor societies where corruption and lack of economic dynamism are rampant. If this is true, agents in poor societies still have a duty to improve their political institutions and bolster their economic development so that more poverty can be eliminated. And the members of wealthier societies have duties to facilitate, and of course also not to block, such improvement. They may have to stop using international institutions (such as the International Monetary Fund or the World Trade Organization) as tools for dominating and exploiting poorer societies, and help turn them into tools for expanding the opportunities of the poor to escape penury. I will defend the proposed view of duties of justice by explaining how it relates to the seven contrasts mentioned. In doing this, I will draw on the five desiderata listed in section 2. I will   7   argue that my proposed account satisfies the desiderata, that it does not neatly coincide with any of the traditional contrasts, and that none of the contrasts fulfills all the desiderata. The text in this section partly draws on, but systematically revises and expands, the discussion on the contrast between justice and humanitarianism presented in section 1.6 of my book From Global Poverty to Global Equality.5 (i) Capturing the stringency of justice A common intuition is that duties of justice are particularly stringent moral demands. Many agree with the view that, as Adam Swift puts it, “[p]olitical philosophy … is a very specific subset of moral philosophy, and one where the stakes are particularly high. It’s not just about what people ought to do, it’s about what people are morally permitted, and sometimes morally required, to make each other do”.6 The account I suggested captures this by saying that duties of justice are prima facie enforceable. However, it might be objected that my account does not fully capture the stringency of justice because it qualifies enforceability by reference to “reasonable costs” to duty bearers. This might seem to render duties of justice less stringent than their contrast with beneficence intuitively involves. On a construal of contrast IV (Enforceability), we would be problematically blurring the distinction between justice and beneficence if we allow duties of justice to turn out to be not enforceable given computation of costs. It would be better to deem such duties demands of beneficence, which are typically less stringent, and not necessarily enforceable. To illustrate this objection, consider two scenarios. Both include duties whose fulfillment involves severe costs to the duty-bearer (such as their inability to pay for housing). The content of the duties in the two cases differs as follows. In the first, Federico pays back a loan to his creditor. In the second, Gillian helps several destitute people by giving them a considerable amount of money. According to the objection I am considering, it seems intuitively correct to   8   subject the second duty, but not the first, to a “reasonable costs” qualification, and this difference is one of the things we want to mark by calling the first a duty of justice and the second a duty of beneficence. The duty of beneficence to help the needy can be limited if its fulfillment involves the severe impoverishment of the duty-bearer, but this caveat does not apply to the duty of justice to pay back a loan. The objection that taking demands of justice to be sensitive to costs would deprive them of their characteristic stringency (as opposed to the lesser stringency of beneficence) is mistaken. First, it seems reasonable that demands of justice be sensitive to costs. This is because justice should attend to the claims of everyone, including duty-bearers besides right-holders.7 Thus, we can reasonably reject the judgment that Federico should sell his home and liquidate all his assets and run to risk it all in a casino tonight even if doing this offers the only opportunity for him to raise enough money to make the payments that are due tomorrow. There may be extenuating circumstances such that someone’s debt payments may be justifiably lowered, or delayed, or cancelled. For example, they may cater for a sufficientarian norm of justice that no one should fall into destitution. Second, even if Gillian is permitted to refrain from giving so much money, she may still have some stringent and demanding duties toward the destitute. Consider the view that it is not wrong to tax people like Gillian to help the destitute. We think that the level of taxation should be determined not only by considering the potential beneficiaries of policies funded by taxation, but also by attending to the situation of those who would be taxed. This point, like the previous one, suggests that duties of justice and sensitivity to costs can legitimately be coupled. Third, we can see some duties of justice as weightier than other duties without having to say that the latter are not duties of justice. There can be demands that outweigh, or even constrain, others, while being all demands of justice. It is of course often difficult to determine the precise   9   relations among different demands of justice, but we can recognize the general point that a plurality of them warranting prima facie enforcement exists. We can then envisage appropriate articulations in particular exercises. A clear and familiar example is Rawls’s “lexical ordering” of his two principles of justice. The first principle protecting equal civil and political liberties constrains the second principle promoting economic justice, and the part of the second principle concerning fair equality of opportunity constrains the other part (the “Difference Principle”) demanding the maximization of income for the worst-off.8 There is a common view according to which duties of justice normally have logical priority over duties of beneficence because the former, unlike the latter, are constitutive of an account of what is rightfully owned.9 Beneficence focuses on what people should do with what is theirs, assuming an account of what belongs to whom. Now, the account proposed here agrees with this view. Some positive duties to help others can be the counterpart of their positive entitlements. We can then justify the claim that rich people like Warren Buffett should be taxed to fund public education for children from destitute families by saying that the destitute children are entitled to the part of the rich’s pre-tax income that could be used to support them. (ii) Enabling rather than suppressing substantive debates A common temptation that should be resisted is to define disputed terms in ways that make some substantive claims couched in such terms impossible. This maneuver or shortcut does not solve substantive problems. The positions rendered definitionally impossible will simply reassert themselves through challenges to the definitions proposed, or by disputing the weight in our overall reasoning of the claims using the terms as defined. Consider contrast II (Negative / Positive). On this contrast, no thing is a duty of justice unless it is a negative duty or a derivative of it. Thus, there is a negative duty of justice not to deprive others of the means of survival. There is no positive duty of justice to provide them with such   10   means (unless such provision is a form of compensation for previous deprivations, or the counterpart of a promise or a contract whose violation would flout a negative duty). Now, this view of justice as based on negative duties should be seen as a substantive conception of justice, not as a claim about the concept of justice. If the latter were asserted, this would beg the question against those who say that people like Warren Buffett have positive duties of justice to contribute to the subsistence of the destitute. If those who think that there are underived positive duties of justice were told that they are thinking about duties of beneficence rather than justice, they will contest the definition of the former as unduly narrow. Alternatively, they will say that duties of justice do not have the primacy often claimed for them (so that an alleged negative duty of justice not to tax Warren Buffett to help the destitute would be outweighed by a positive duty of beneficence to make him help them, even if this involves taxing Buffett). Hence it is better to keep the definition of justice broad enough to make room for substantive debate. Thus, a libertarian view of all fundamental duties of justice as negative should be seen as a substantive theory of justice, not simply as a definition of the concept of justice.10 A defense of it through a definitional maneuver would be a Pyrrhic victory. Does what I have just said warrant the rejection of contrast II? A defender of this contrast could reply that we should accept it because of its fit with the first desideratum concerning the stringency of justice. This is because a negative duty regarding a certain object is normally weightier than a positive duty regarding the same object. Stealing food from the hungry is worse than refraining from giving them food. But this rebuttal is unsatisfactory. First, it does not ground a general claim of supremacy of negative over positive duties (which seems necessary for contrast II to hold). A negative duty regarding a certain object may have less moral weight than another positive duty regarding another object when the two conflict in practice. My duty not to deprive you of access to an object you own without your consent may have less weight than my   11   duty to save someone’s life. This is so, for example, when I can only take a mortally wounded person to the hospital by taking your car. Second, some negative duties may be weightier than positive duties with the same object without this entailing that the former are, and the latter are not, duties of justice. Even if they have unequal weight, both duties may be sufficiently weighty to be duties of justice. Thus, the duty to help secure educational opportunities for destitute children may have less weight than the duty to refrain from prohibiting destitute children from attending school, but it may be weighty enough to justify taxing Warren Buffett to fund its implementation. The account I have proposed is broad enough to enable the substantive discussion that contrast II represses. Similar considerations apply regarding contrasts IV and VI. Consider contrast IV (Enforceability). The problem with this contrast is that justifiable enforceability is neither sufficient nor necessary for something to be a duty of justice. Some contributions could be justifiably enforced without being duties of justice. For example, Allen Buchanan has argued that some forms of enforcement can be seen as securing the provision of certain collective goods that do not respond to correlative rights. Buchanan’s discussion of this thesis may be problematic, as the collective goods he mentions—clean air, energy conservation, national defense—may in fact be the objects of rights.11 But we can imagine cases in which rights are not involved. An example might be the promotion of certain cultural practices of the kind Rawls discusses when he identifies the tasks of a hypothetical “exchange branch” of the state in a well-ordered society.12 An instance of this is public funding for opera houses. Another example might be some forms of renewed assistance to people who repeatedly and blamably squander the resources they receive.13 Justifiable coercion is also not a necessary condition for justice. Sometimes coercive enforcement of certain demands may be all things considered unreasonable. An example of debate over this issue concerns the introduction of “speech codes” that impose penalties on agents performing   12   speech acts that carry clearly racist or sexist content. Some argue that although people have a duty of justice not to speak to others in racist or sexist ways, it would be overall a bad idea to have the state patrol linguistic practice. This position might be mistaken, but it is not conceptually incoherent. What explains the wide support for contrast IV? It seems to me that at least part of this support depends on the important intuition that demands of justice are strong enough for their enforcement to warrant serious consideration because of the involvement of rights claims. The reference to rights establishes a strong, stringent ground for proposals of enforcement that is lacking in cases of beneficence. But my proposed account captures this point while avoiding the pitfalls of IV by seeing enforceability as being only prima facie and conditional upon considerations of feasibility and reasonable costs. Proposals of enforcement can be rejected when they involve unreasonable costs, or when they would not really help fulfill a relevant duty. The point just made also affects some versions of contrast VI (Institutional / Personal) that see justice as only ranging over coercive institutions. As G. A. Cohen has argued, some duties of justice that constitute the ethos or moral culture of a just society may inform choices by individuals that are beyond the purview of coercive legal structures.14 A society without a racist culture would in one respect be more just than a society with a racist culture even if the coercive institutions of both societies were the same. An institutionalist about justice could reply that the importance of an ethos for justice can be accounted for while insisting that only institutions populate the primary focus of demands of justice. This is because institutions have significant cultural effects and can thus help shape a society’s ethos.15 This true and important point is not however sufficient to justify an exclusive primary focus on institutions. One reason for this is that the relation between a society’s institutions and its culture is one of reciprocal rather than unidirectional influence. A certain   13   cultural environment may be necessary for certain institutions to arise in the first place. This point is crucial when we address the (relatively underexplored) issue of the accessibility of just institutions besides the (often explored) issue of their stability. The latter can to a large extent be accounted for by considering how just institutions shape political culture by socializing people in certain ways. But the former cannot readily be accounted for in this way. An important part of the struggle for justice in unjust societies is the generation of a sufficiently strong political will supporting reform, and this often involves an ideological battle in civil society through which political actors succeed in shaping practical attitudes of large sectors of society before new, just institutions formalizing the spirit of those attitudes are introduced. A striking example of this is the long cultural struggle by feminists before legal frameworks implementing nondiscrimination were established.16 Furthermore, it is worth noting that some demands of justice are directly rather than indirectly focused on people’s informal attitudes and choices in their interactions with each other. Daily, informal interactions in which persons address each other with respect are part of what a just society consists in. Even if institutions were enough to shape such attitudes (something I find unlikely to be true17), their role would be partly instrumental, and thus not wholly constitutive of the primary focus of justice, as holders of contrast VI seem to assume. (iii) Determinateness We want a concept of justice that is tolerably determinate. A difficulty with contrast I (Due) in this respect is that it does not fully capture the fact that duties of justice are different from other moral demands. The characterization of justice as giving people their due is too broad. On this account, most moral duties could be seen as a duty of justice, as most actions that are moral duties (rather than, say, something that would be praiseworthy but not wrong not to do), could be construed as delivering what is due, or owed, to someone. Consider the duties to fulfill the following promises: to call you on Wednesday to go to the cinema and to pay back the money   14   you loaned me at the agreed upon time. Both duties involve my giving you what is due to you. But the first, unlike the second, does not strike us as a good candidate for a duty of justice. As I said in section 2, my proposal partly absorbs contrast V (Rights) because it sees duties of justice as responding to correlative rights. However, my proposal does not simply collapse into this contrast. One reason is that, as we saw, it also refers to prima facie enforceability. Doing this makes the concept of justice more determinate. Not every right warrants demands of justice. Some moral rights (such as your right that your friend show up at the cinema at the agreed upon time) may not be even prima facie justifiably enforceable. On the other hand, we should not be too strict about determinateness because this may lead to overlooking important moral issues. Consider for example a version of contrast III (and a view of contrast V that is tied to it), according to which someone’s right to an object is only linked to duties of justice on the part of someone else if those duties are perfect (if they are duties to do certain clearly specified things to preserve or promote access to that object by the right-holder). This seems to me to be an unduly narrow account of rights that impoverishes our thinking about them. It overlooks the possibility that we can identify rights with different levels of precision, so that some rights may correlate to both perfect and imperfect duties.18 Take for example a right to health care. Governments have perfect duties not to arbitrarily deprive any resident of access to existing public heath care programs. They may not, for example, discriminate on the basis of political opinion, race, ethnicity, or gender. But surely governments also have a duty to create some needed health care programs that do not yet exist. This duty is imperfect because it is indeterminate as to what programs of the many that are possible should be chosen (when not all can be feasibly and readily introduced at reasonable cost). It can be made more determinate at the level of policy. But its more general and imperfect (and thus somewhat indeterminate) form is itself significant. It is one of the reasonable counterparts of a constitution that includes social   15   rights, and citizens and courts could press governments to acknowledge it and take steps to fulfill it in some of the many ways possible.19 Thus, the distinction between perfect and imperfect duties does not provide a model for the distinction between justice and beneficence. As we saw, there can be duties of justice that are imperfect. As an additional and important example, consider the duty to contribute to institutional change in an unjust society. This is one of the “natural duties of justice” for individuals mentioned by Rawls in A Theory of Justice.20 It is clearly imperfect because it does not by itself specify what, and how much, any person should do to fight injustice.21 Furthermore, there may be duties of beneficence that are perfect. An example could be a duty to help certain people escape circumstances of severe deprivation when they can only do so with our help, they are the only ones who need our help, we can help at reasonable cost, and the deprivation they face is the result of their repeatedly squandering resources previously received (perhaps in fulfillment of duties of sufficientarian or egalitarian justice). (iv) Capturing the critical role of justice A fourth desideratum in accounting for duties of justice is that we avoid automatic deference to the status quo. A critical and dynamic attitude toward our current circumstances is among the crucial things we expect the standpoint of justice to help us achieve. An important case in this respect is the ability to support dynamic duties to expand current feasible sets of political action so that certain just distributions that are infeasible (or have very low feasibility) in the present become feasible (or more feasible) in the future.22 This helps notice a further problem with contrast III (Perfect / Imperfect). For example, it would be a mistake to say that there is not a duty of justice to help eradicate global poverty because it is currently unclear who should do what for whom, or because we currently do not have international institutions scheduling and enforcing specific forms of contribution securing the eradication of poverty for all. Currently imperfect   16   duties can, and often should, be made perfect through the generation of new forms of collective action and institutional structures articulating specific provisions.23 It is not unreasonable to see the introduction of such articulation as a demand of justice. But its ground may be the importance of the pre-existing imperfect duty of justice to eradicate poverty that such articulation would help specify and implement. It would have been a worrisome capitulation to the status quo to deny the existence of these demands before the construction of welfare states in domestic contexts. A similar mistake at the global level could and arguably should be avoided. The identification of perfect duties and the existence of institutional mechanisms are extremely important. They can foster efficiency by coordinating the action of many agents, they can help identify a fair allocation of responsibilities given agents’ diverse needs, abilities, and associative relations, and they can cement motivation to comply for those who are not sufficiently morally motivated and for those who need assurance that others will also do their share. Thus, we do need to focus extensively on institutional structures when we develop a conception of justice. (Of course, their coercive nature besides their far-reaching influence also makes their justifiability an important concern.24) But this does not entail that there could be no duties of justice that are not already institutionally specified. This point obviously affects some versions of contrast VI (Institutional / Personal) in addition to contrast III (Perfect / Imperfect). We have already identified several reasons for rejecting the reduction of duties of justice to institutionally articulated duties. Another reason that relates to the desiderata of avoiding question-begging views and the critical role of justice is the following. It is not a conceptual impossibility to think of a just society that has no robust, or coercive, institutional structure. An example might be an anarchist society securing liberty and equality for all through arrangements that are thoroughly voluntary.25 Although such a society is hardly achievable, its characterization as just is not a conceptual mistake. Furthermore, a picture of it may work as an ideal with the   17   help of which other, more feasible social structures can be evaluated and compared. Some may turn out to be preferable if they approximate the ideal more closely than others. (v) Illuminating practices A further desideratum for an understanding of justice is that it should help us make sense of problems in current political practices. For example, an understanding of distributive justice as ranging over enforceable rights is in tune with the modern emergence of the view that duties to eradicate severe poverty and reduce inequality are among the key responsibilities of states.26 This desideratum should also apply to the current debate on global justice, in which we can identify two important shifts. They involve the emergence of discussions over whether responsibilities of justice can rely on associative relations different from co-membership of a state and on humanist claims concerning important interests of human beings regardless of associative ties. Both shifts involve a departure from a narrow construal of justice which, as a variant of contrast VI (Institutional / Personal), holds that two persons can have duties of distributive justice toward each other only if they are both subject to state institutions that act coercively and in their name.27 The first shift involves the view that two persons may share duties of distributive justice if they are intertwined in associative frameworks that are less comprehensive than a state but are still morally consequential.28 A typical example concerns relations of deep economic interdependence. Their existence may give rise to duties to avoid exploitation of members of poorer societies (for example through unfair bargaining mechanisms in international institutions such as the World Trade Organization, or through humiliating labor conditions in sweatshops run by multinational corporations in relatively poor countries). The previous shift is compatible with contrast VII (Associative / Non-associative), but demands a wider view of the kinds of associative facts that give rise to concerns of distributive justice. The second shift is more radical, and challenges it. According to this contrast distributive   18   justice is confined to duties arising among co-members of already existing associations (economic, political, national, etc.). On this contrast, a humanist view of justice according to which some duties of justice correlate to rights that protect interests that human beings as such have is a category mistake. But such a humanist view is an important strand in the contemporary theory and practice of global justice. Universal sufficientarian claims against severe poverty are a central part of human rights discourse. And some philosophers are starting to argue that some egalitarian demands regarding some goods (such as health care, education, and work opportunities) can also take non-associativist forms. If we recognize that all human persons are ultimate units of equal moral concern and respect for everyone, then we might entertain the thought that we have duties to help others access important advantages even if due to the natural lottery they were born outside of our associative networks.29 This view has practical significance for debates about the strength and content of global duties of aid, and about the extent to which borders should be open to immigrants. The desideratum of illuminating current political practice would be flouted if we work with a concept of justice that does not help us grasp these shifts as expressing valid moves in the debate about what justice demands. The desiderata concerning the critical and dynamic role of considerations of justice and concerning the need to avoid begging important substantive questions should also make us suspicious of an understanding of justice based on contrast VII. Eliminating humanist conceptions through a definitional maneuver would be philosophically unsatisfactory. It would also uncritically defer to the status quo, which includes on the part of many the belief that they do not have duties of justice tracking rights of human beings who are not already co-members in some parochial association. To reach a considered view about what is the just way to approach the ongoing process of globalization, we need to be able to raise and   19   assess diverse associativist and humanist proposals. And to enable that discussion, we need a capacious concept of justice like the one I proposed. 4. Objections and elaborations I conclude by considering some possible objections to, and elaborations of, the account of duties of justice presented above. (1) A first worry is that the reference to “important conditions or goods” in the characterization of duties and rights of justice may not be necessary. Imagine a contract between Juan and Peter in which Peter commits to giving Juan a massage for a fee. Juan is entitled to Peter’s massage, and perhaps Peter can be said to have a duty of justice to honor the contract. But the good involved is not important. In response, we can make two points. First, we can consider specific rights and duties as cases of wider principles. In the example discussed, we can consider the importance of making and honoring contracts. Having access to successful practices of this kind is clearly an important good. Alternatively, it could be that some instances of a practice are relatively unimportant (as in the example above) while others are quite important (as in, say, transfers of real estate or full- time job contracts). We can then simply distinguish subsets of contract rights and duties, and say that only those ranging over sufficiently important goods give rise to rights and duties of justice. (The standard of “sufficient importance”, of course, is a matter of substantive conception, not of concept.) (2) Another worry targets the component of “prima facie enforceability” in the account of duties of justice proposed. The general difficulty concerns the explanatory significance of this component when contrasted with the other component referring to rights. It seems that in the order of explanation, something is a duty of justice because it protects or promotes the fulfillment   20   of an important right, and a duty is enforceable because it is a duty of justice. It does not seem true to say that something is a duty of justice because it is (inter alia) enforceable. In response, I agree that referring to rights is explanatorily more important than referring to prima facie enforceability (this is why I said, in section 2, that enforcement is justifiable when— inter alia—it is necessary or strongly contributory to the fulfillment of rights). But I think that both are explanatory significant. Prima facie enforceability is a dependent, but relevant component. This is because intuitively duties of justice involve, prima facie, justifiable limitations on people’s liberty to act. What the worry just mentioned forces me to acknowledge is that there is an explanatory structure within the account of justice such that the importance of the relevant rights determines (together with other considerations such as feasibility and reasonable costs) the justifiability of the enforcement of the duties to protect or promote their fulfillment. (3) The previous point helps me to address another worry, and to entertain a reformulation of the account proposed. The worry is that the account of justice proposed may force us to exclude imperfect duties from the domain of justice because they may be unenforceable even prima facie. If Gillian has an imperfect duty to help the destitute, she has discretion as to whom to help and how to do it. Given this discretion, we have no clear target for enforcement.30 A first response is that enforcement may still be possible when the duty-bearer has discretion. One way to do this is to demand that the agent show periodically, at defined times, that they have chosen some of the possible ways to fulfill their imperfect duty or face penalties. The agent still operates with a disjunctive set of possible ways to help (for example, they can help A or B or C…). But they can be asked to show that they have chosen at least one of the items in the disjunction. There is also the option, considered above, of “perfecting” the imperfect duty through institutional specification by for example demanding that Gillian pay taxes, which are in turn   21   used to fund specific policies of aid for certain individuals. But important as it is, this solution is partial, as there will still be some additional duties that remain imperfect. The choice by officials of relevant policies to assist the destitute may itself involve some discretion. This point has been overlooked by proponents of the strategy of “perfecting duties.” Here the imperfection is eliminated at one level but at the cost of generating it at another. Thus, this strategy cannot yield the elimination of imperfect duties. This circumstance is not, however, a source of despair if we reject contrast III, as I recommend in this paper. There may be other cases in which certain duties are unenforceable because they are simply not the kind of thing that can be enforced and are, thus, not even prima facie candidates for enforcement. This might hold in the case of certain psychological and cultural traits and dispositions that are not directly under the voluntary control of agents (such as a spirited concern for the plight of the worse off, and a readiness to participate in democratic politics when there is no legal articulation of the relevant duties). But these phenomena can still be shaped, indirectly and over the long-term, by agents. We can increase the presence of such traits and dispositions through education, material incentives, and other mechanisms. And we can be under prima facie enforceable duties to support the use of those mechanisms. For example, we may have duties to publicly fund educational opportunities, democratize access to the mass media, and much else that affects people’s knowledge and attitudes. This is another case of application of the idea of dynamic duties (see 3.iv above). A more radical response to the current worry would be to revise the account of duties of justice by relativizing the enforceability clause even further. In addition to seeing it as explanatorily dependent on the clause referring to important rights, we can see prima facie enforceability as typically, but not always or necessarily a feature of duties of justice. This could be a case in which strict analysis in terms of sufficient and necessary conditions breaks down,   22   and we rest content with identifying a set of typical features of a concept. On this weaker approach to conceptual inquiry, the characterizing features need not all hold in every case. Another possibility is to see enforceability as marking a species within the genus of justice (as pertaining, for example, to something that could be called “political” or “institutional justice”). (4) A further worry is that the acceptance of imperfect duties of justice is incompatible with the view that duties of justice correlate with rights. Some could argue that only duties that are clearly directed to specifiable claimants can correlate with rights. If Gillian can fulfill her duty to help some within a set of three persons, none of those persons has a claim against Gillian that they specifically be helped by her. This challenge can be answered in many ways. Some were already mentioned (when referring to mechanisms for “perfecting” duties). But the issue of directedness can also be tackled by noticing that Gillian’s imperfect duty is in principle directed to all of the three potential beneficiaries. Each has a claim that they be considered as a potential beneficiary. None would be wronged by Gillian if another potential beneficiary is chosen in their stead (as Gillian is permitted to choose), but they would be wronged if they were not so considered, and, of course, if none of them were helped. If the relevant duty is primarily based on the importance to the destitute of avoiding their penury (rather than, say, on the sense of elevation that Gillian would get from helping) then the duty already has a direction toward right-holders. Notice that this directedness should orient not only immediate responses in the present, but also strategies of action for the future. Besides having the normal duty to help some of the destitute now, Gillian, together with others, may have a dynamic duty to foster social arrangements under which all (or more) of the destitute get the help they need. Another possible response is to adopt a narrow view of rights as bounded up with perfect duties but to relax their characterization. We could do what was suggested above when referring   23   to enforceability, and see claimability (narrowly conceived) as a typical, but not always necessary, feature of justice. 31 Still another response is to drop acceptance of imperfect duties as duties of justice. This would simplify the discussion in (3) and (4) because there would be no need to contest or revise the reference to any of the components of the account of duties of justice proposed. However, my current state of reflective equilibrium says that we should avoid the dramatic surgery involved in this suggestion. It would require, implausibly, that we omit from the set of duties of justice some that seem to be among their paradigmatic cases (such as the duty to contribute to the reform of unjust societies and to support just ones). (5) Another potential worry is that my account of justice is too beneficiary-centered. This impression might arise because rights are said to be based on the importance of certain conditions or goods to right-holders. This seems to omit consideration of the perspective of duty-bearers. But the interest of a putative right-holder in certain conditions or goods is not sufficient for grounding a right to it; we also need to show that the agents with the putative correlative duties of protection or promotion in fact ought to acknowledge such duties. I agree that the perspective of duty-bearers is important in determining whether there is a right. Such a perspective is already taken into account when we see the enforceability of the implementation of demands of justice as depending on their feasibility and reasonable cost (which partly concern the duty-bearers’ ability to do what is demanded without shouldering unacceptable burdens). I now suggest that such concerns of feasibility and reasonable cost can also be seen to apply to the determination of the existence of the duties themselves. We can bring the perspective of duty-bearers further into focus when developing a conception of rights. In my own view, we can proceed on the basis of the following schema: If A (a right- holder) has a right to O (a certain object involving an important condition or good) against B (a   24   duty-bearer), then there are feasible and reasonable demands on B that they respect or promote, in some significant ways to be specified, A’s access to O. The specification of what B owes to A regarding O tracks the moral importance of A’s interest in O, the feasible ways for B to respect or promote A’s access to O, and the subset of such feasible forms of respect and promotion that do not involve morally unacceptable burdens on B or others (given the importance of their own interests) and on A (given the importance of other interests of A besides that concerning access to O). The specification and justification of A’s right is coterminous with the specification and justification of B’s (and other duty-bearers’) duties. No right is justified only by considering what would benefit A. Even if access to O would greatly benefit A, A does not have a right to O against B if B cannot feasibly affect A’s access to O, or could only do it in advantageous ways to A by incurring unreasonable costs. As we identify B’s duties to A, we can also factor in additional moral considerations such as responsibility and fairness. Sometimes the fact that A’s lack of access to O has resulted from blamable voluntary choices by A may diminish B’s obligations; sometimes B’s obligation may be more stringent if A’s lack of access to O is the result of what B has blamably done; and sometimes the computation of the extent of sacrifice B can reasonably incur in supporting A has to include what other agents C can and should do. The kind of holistic assessment just mentioned would also help capture the multiple considerations that can go into the identification and justification of rights and duties of justice. These may depend on associative concerns (such as those regarding justification of coercion, reciprocity in economic cooperation, equity in relations of production and political decision- making so that exploitation and domination are avoided). My rejection of a definitional reduction of the concept of justice to associative responsibilities does not deny that justice includes them. Its point is to prevent a definitional suppression of other responsibilities of justice that are not associative (as arguably at least some human rights based ones are).   25   Rights of justice, as I acknowledged, cannot simply be articulated by reference to the demand side (the interests of right-holders). We also need to illuminate the perspective of duty-bearers. But we do not need to assume as a conceptual matter the substantive view that the demand side can never, as it were, outstrip the general negative duties and special associative responsibilities of suppliers. A substantive view of justice as responding positively (within the limits of what is reasonably feasible) to the important interests of outsiders is a lively option that must be taken into account and engaged in normative argument. There are views of justice as reduced to duties not to take goods away from others, or as only recognizing frameworks of cooperation in which every participant “breaks even” (never giving more than they receive), or as deepening mutual service (when it goes beyond strict equivalence) only when it happens among people already wrapped in the flag of a particular nation, state, or common economic venture. But these views are just some candidates among others. They have to face the alternatives rather than outsource the concerns those alternatives articulate to the realm of beneficence. What would be lost if such concerns are indeed outsourced to the realm of beneficence? What would be lost, I think, is the opportunity to see how those concerns may affect the content, existence, and weight of the negative and associative duties that we already accept. Expanding the circle of justice forces us to seek more perspicuous, integrated, and practically lucid pictures of what we owe to each other.32 We should take everyone’s important interests to heart before deciding whether we can permissibly see some of them as giving rise only to weaker or supplementary calls on our charity. (6) How significant is the discussion about the distinction between justice and beneficence? Why should we care about what does and what does not belong to justice?33 Perhaps we could do all the theoretical work we need to do if we drop reference to justice and beneficence and simply talk about the different reasonable moral demands we can make on each other: some negative, some   26   positive; some grounded in rights, some not; some institutionally articulated, some interpersonal; some associative, some general; etcetera. We could simply identify these different demands, their mutual constraints, and their relative weight in different domains of application. What is crucial, it might be said, is that we have a clear picture of the different duties that capture what we owe to each other, their content, relation, and weight. Whether we call them duties of justice or beneficence is immaterial. On reflection, I think that we should keep referring to justice (construed as I suggest) as different from beneficence for four reasons. A first reason is pragmatic. The invocation of the distinction between justice and beneficence is pervasive in moral and political theory and practice. A call for dropping the terms “justice” and “beneficence” is not likely to succeed. Furthermore, it is common to say that demands of justice are more important than, or have priority over, demands of beneficence. If we want to make sure that certain important demands (such as those that are positive, and go beyond state-based associative reasons) are not downplayed or made to wait, it is wise to construe them as part of justice. It could be replied that if the distinction between justice and beneficence, with its in-built hierarchy, is bound to remain, it is also likely to fail to include the capacious view of justice that I recommend. Is not that view arbitrary in any case? The answer (and this is my second point) is that the construal I offered is not arbitrary. As I said at the outset, it is not a mere elucidation, and so it is not meant to simply report current usage. But no view that merely reports current usage will be satisfactory because there is no thoroughly agreed upon usage anyway. So we need a constructive proposal. The proposal I offer, on the other hand, is not a mere stipulation. It builds upon ideas of rights and enforceability, which are in fact quite central to the actual practice of moral and political debate (even if it construes them in a specific way).   27   Third, my proposal about how to construe justice meets the five reasonable desiderata. It helps us identify stringent demands, enables us to engage in important substantive debates, is tolerably determinate, helps us fulfill the critical role of considerations of justice, and makes it possible to clarify the stakes in important contemporary debates about justice (especially about global justice). A concept of justice with those virtues is worth using. Finally, although capacious, my account of justice does not swallow all putative demands of beneficence.34 Some of those demands are in fact absorbed by justice (as is the case with easy rescues attending to urgent needs35), but others remain beyond justice (as is the case with some ways of benefitting others that cannot plausibly be construed as responding to prima facie entitlements). My account enables the grasp of the wealth of reasons of justice, but it also honors the widespread intuition that there are some ways of making the life of others better that are not demanded by justice. We do need a separate conceptual domain for beneficence. (7) Another worry about my account of duties of justice is that it fails to capture the relational nature of justice and the active dimension of persons. The account seems to be non-relational but instead focused on end-states and it seems to see those states as befalling persons in a passive way. The account, it might be said, is fixated on the issue of what some person A gets. But it should, instead, focus on how another person B treats A, on what kinds of relations exist between A and B, and on what A and B have done to each other. Access to goods is an important, but subordinate dimension. Justice should range over persons as related and active agents, not over persons as isolated and passive recipients. Otherwise, we cannot capture the difference between B’s duties toward A if the disadvantage experienced by A is the result of a natural disaster and when it is the result of relations of economic or political exploitation or domination imposed by B. B’s action to help improve A’s condition is, in the first case, a matter of charity, whereas in the second it is a matter of justice proper.36 Besides illuminating the involvement of B, we must   28   also consider the agency of A and ponder whether A deserves B’s support, and what kind of support is fitting if A is to function as an independent person. This worry captures two important intuitions, but does not debunk my broad account of justice. The intuitions are that it matters for justice how circumstances of advantage and disadvantage result from social relations, and that it also matters that people see themselves and each other in those relations as active agents with power and responsibility. But those intuitions can be captured without surrendering the approach proposed. If B helps A to overcome the penury resulting from a natural disaster, B could be adopting a certain relational stance toward A, one in which the penury of another human being may trigger an obligation of support. We should construe the idea of a relational stance capaciously. It may include associative concerns about non-exploitation and non-domination, and general negative duties to avoid undue harm. But it may also involve a general commitment not to let fellow human beings down when they are stuck in penury. Some forms of moral solidarity might be duties of justice (while others, of course, might be duties of beneficence: for example, we may have a duty of justice to help provide clothes to the destitute, but we might have only a duty of beneficence to give them their favorite clothes37). In such cases, when we consider others’ states of disadvantage we do not only ask “Have I done that to them?” or “Was it my fault?” We also ask “May I allow that to go on?” or “May I let that happen to them?” Injustice may be done to others through indifference. Several issues of agency are of course important. Resources for support do not normally materialize without being the result of productive efforts by some agents (thus the reference to fairness to duty-bearers mentioned in 4(5) above). And those helped are not to be seen as mere passive receptacles of beneficial stuff, but as agents who could be participants in their own amelioration38 (and sometimes morally responsible for bringing about their own disadvantage). But we can, and on some substantive views of justice we should, also pay attention to the   29   significance of need and mutual dependency. A radical ideal of independence is arguably infeasible and undesirable. It is part of what persons are that they need the support of others to avoid the bad and the wrong and to pursue the good and the right. We can, and arguably we should, relate to each other so as to respond to that vulnerability with solidarity. Persons are not merely passive recipients, but they are passive to an important extent. They should not have to feel humiliated if they are helped, and they should not have to feel guilt when they help others. We can capture these points by acknowledging (multiply qualified) general rights and duties of justice of mutual support. (8) I conclude these reflections by considering briefly one of the hardest issues in the discussion about the idea of justice: How do we identify the difference between a concept and a conception? Is this difference sharp or porous? A view I find worth entertaining is that this difference is in fact not tight. We can see the concept of justice as marking a territory of debate that is valuable to identify and explore. But the boundaries of that territory depend on our substantive interest in areas of it, and in our concern for engaging each other in its examination even if we disagree about the content of the important areas. On this view, our conceptual commitments are partly driven by our substantive normative beliefs. The former are meant to help us articulate, voice, and assess the latter. But why include in a concept the possibility of a conception one considers false? Because (inter alia) one has a quite general, substantive commitment to engage other human beings in argument about what we owe to each other. To do this, we need conceptual tools that allow us to work (and also quarrel) together. I realize that this picture of the debate about concept and conceptions of justice may assume a humanist cosmopolitan commitment to the framing importance of equal respect and concern for all human persons. But if one cannot fully disengage concept from conception at some point, this seems a point worth resting at.   30   Acknowledgments For helpful comments or conversations I thank referees, Arash Abizadeh, Elizabeth Ashford, Charles Beitz, Rainer Forst, Francisco Garcia Gibson, Mariano Garreta-Leclercq, Waheed Hussain, Carl Knight, Rahul Kumar, Barbara Herman, Louis-Philippe Hodgson, Alistair Macleod, Julio Montero, Mark Nelson, Henry Richardson, Andrea Sangiovanni, Peter Singer, Laura Valentini, Alex Voorhoeve, and participants in colloquia at the Centro de Investigaciones Filosoficas (Buenos Aires), Princeton University Center for Human Values, Queen’s University, University of Montreal, and Glasgow University. My research was supported by a grant from the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada. Note on contributor A native of Argentina, Pablo Gilabert is an Associate Professor in the Department of Philosophy at Concordia University (Montreal, Canada). He has been an HLA Hart Visiting Fellow at the University of Oxford, a DAAD Fellow at the University of Frankfurt, a Visiting Fellow at the Australian National University, and a Laurance S. Rockefeller Visiting Faculty Fellow in the Center for Human Values at Princeton University. His papers appeared in journals such as The Journal of Political Philosophy, Political Theory, The Philosophical Quarterly, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Philosophical Studies, Political Studies and Ethical Theory and Moral Practice. He is the author of From Global Poverty to Global Equality. A Philosophical Exploration (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012).   31   References Ashford, Elizabeth, 2007. The duties imposed by the human right to basic necessities. In: T. Pogge, ed., Freedom from poverty as a human right. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 183-218. Beitz, Charles, 2009. The idea of human rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Buchanan, Allen, 1987. Justice and charity. Ethics, 97, 558-575. Buchanan, Allen, 2004. Justice, legitimacy, and self-determination. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Caney, Simon, 2011. Humanity, associations, and global justice. Monist, 94, 506-534. Cohen, Gerald, 2008. Rescuing justice and equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Cohen, Joshua, 2002. Taking people as they are? Philosophy and Public Affairs, 30, 363-386. Cohen, Joshua and Sabel, Charles, 2006. Extra republicam nulla justitia? Philosophy and public affairs, 34, 147-175. Fleischacker, Samuel, 2004. A short history of distributive justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Forst, Rainer, 2012. The right to justification. New York: Columbia University Press. Gauri, Varun, and Brinks, Daniel, 2012. Human rights as demands for communicative action. Journal of political philosophy, 29, 407-431. Gilabert, Pablo, 2009. The feasibility of basic socioeconomic human rights. A conceptual exploration. Philosophical quarterly, 59, 559-581. Gilabert, Pablo, 2010. Kant and the claims of the poor. Philosophy and phenomenological research, 81, 382-418. Gilabert, Pablo, 2011a. Humanist and political perspectives on human rights. Political theory, 39, 439-467. Gilabert, Pablo, 2011b. Feasibility and socialism. Journal of political philosophy, 19, 52-63.   32   Gilabert, Pablo, 2012. From global poverty to global equality. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Gilabert, Pablo, 2013. The capability approach and the debate between humanist and political perspectives on human rights. A critical survey. Human rights review, 14, 299-325. Gilabert, Pablo, 2015. The socialist principle ‘from each according to their abilities, to each according to their needs’. Journal of social philosophy, 46, 197-225. Gramsci, Antonio, 2000. The Antonio Gramsci reader, ed. D. Forgacs. New York: NYU Press. Kagan, Shelly, 1998. Normative ethics. Boulder, CO: Westview Press. Hart, HLA, 1994. The concept of law, 2nd. ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Miller, David, 1999. Principles of social justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Miller, David, 2007. National responsibility and global justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Miller, Richard, 2010. Globalizing justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Nagel, Thomas, 2005. The problem of global justice. Philosophy and public affairs, 33, 113-147. Narveson, Jan, 1988. The libertarian idea. Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press. Nozick, Robert, 1974. Anarchy, state and utopia. New York: Basic Books Nozick, Robert, 1981. Philosophical explanations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Nussbaum, Martha, 2000. Duties of justice, duties of material aid: Cicero’s problematic legacy. Journal of political philosophy, 8, 176-206. O’Neill, Onora, 1996. Toward justice and virtue. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Pogge, Thomas, 2008. World poverty and human rights, 2nd. ed. Cambridge: Polity. Rawls, John, 1999a. A theory of justice, rev. ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Rawls, John, 1999b. The law of peoples. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Sangiovanni, Andrea, 2007. Global justice, reciprocity, and the state. Philosophy and public affairs, 35, 2-39.   33   Sen, Amartya, 2004. Elements of a theory of human rights. Philosophy and public affairs, 32, 315-356. Sen, Amartya, 2009. The idea of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Shue, Henry, 1988. Mediating duties. Ethics, 98, 687-704. Singer, Peter, 1972. Famine, affluence, and morality. Philosophy and public affairs, 1, 229-243. Swift, Adam, 2006. Political philosophy, 2nd. ed. Cambridge: Polity. Tan, Kok-Chor, 2004. Justice without borders. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Van Parijs, Philippe, 2007. International distributive justice. In: R. Goodin, P. Pettit, T. Pogge eds., A companion to contemporary political philosophy, 2nd .ed. Oxford: Blackwell, 638-652. Waldron, Jeremy, 1993. Liberal rights. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Wiggins, David, 2006. Ethics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 2009. Philosophical investigations, 4rd. ed. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.                                                                                                                 1 For the distinction between concept and conception see Rawls (1999a, p. 5) and Hart (1994, pp. 160, 246). 2 The phrases “conditions and goods,” “entitlements,” “rights,” and “duties,” are broad enough to allow for whatever a conception takes to be the distributively relevant (e.g. they allow comparative considerations about the standing of persons in relation to others). 3 Some such features (even if they do not all apply in every case) may mark the “family resemblance” amongst duties of justice. On “family resemblance” see Wittgenstein (2009, sects. 65-7). The use of this approach might make a proposal less open to challenge via counterexamples. The latter can be seen as identifying borderline cases that lie beyond the core of the concept. For deployments of this strategy see section 4. 4 For the point that justice concerns giving each person their due, see Wiggins (2006, Lecture 10) and Cohen (2008, p. 7). For elucidation and critical discussion of contrasts II through V, see Buchanan (1987). For a presentation of contrasts IV and V see Miller (2007, pp. 248-9). See also Miller (1999, p.76): “One test of the distinction between justice and humanity is whether those in need are regarded as having enforceable claims to the resources that will meet their needs, and correspondingly whether potential donors are regarded as being under enforceable obligations to provide those resources.” An example of contrast VI appears in Tan (2004, p.21). Tan actually focuses on the related question of the distinction between “justice” and “ethics,” claiming (on the basis of an interpretation of Rawls’s theory of justice) that the former has an “institutional focus” while the latter has an “interactional focus.” Tan distinguishes his view from Pogge’s view, according to which an “institutional approach not only has an institutional focus, but it also has an institutional basis or justification,” and he does not “share the justificatory claim in Pogge’s approach that we have duties of justice only in so far as we are causally via our institutions responsible for injustices” (Ibid.). For Pogge’s view, see his (2008). Rawls (1999b, pp. 195ff.) contrasts distributive justice and humanitarian assistance. Contrast VII is embraced by the majority of philosophers in the current debate on global justice (although the normatively relevant forms of association are characterized in different ways—see notes 27-28 below). For challenges to it see, however, Caney (2011) and Gilabert (2012, chs. 5-6). My discussion focuses on contemporay debates. For historical explorations, see Fleischacker (2004); and Nussbaum ((2000). 5 Gilabert (2012, pp. 11-8). This paper differs from that earlier text in the following ways: an account of deliberative interpretive proposals is advanced, the characterization of justice is changed to include reference to access to goods   34                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                           and conditions rather than merely to advantages, the list of desiderata is explicitly stated and is expanded to include determinateness and illumination of practices, the contrast Associative / Non-associative is added, the arguments defending the proposed characterization of justice are rephrased to make them sharper and additional arguments are advanced. The final section of this paper takes the discussion further by addressing possible challenges and by providing further elaborations of the proposed characterization of justice. Finally, this paper does not endorse a deflationary conclusion about the importance of the distinction between justice and beneficence. 6 Swift (2006, p. 6). 7 Nozick (1981, pp. 498-504). As Francisco Garcia Gibson pointed out to me, considerations about costs to agents may affect duties of justice in different ways (e.g. by impacting their content, weight, or enforceability). 8 Rawls (1999, pp. 266-7). 9 See, e.g., Van Parijs (2007, p. 641). 10 For the libertarian view, see Nozick (1974) and Narveson (1988). 11 Buchanan (1987, pp. 562-9). 12 Rawls (1999a, pp. 249-51, 291-2). 13 Miller (2007, p. 249). 14 Cohen (2008, ch. 3). See also Sen (2009, pp. x-xi, 10, 67-9, 75-86). 15 See Cohen (2002). See also Rawls, (1999a, sect. 41). 16 Another instructive example is Gramsci’s view that socialist transformations in Western democratic societies are only likely to succeed if socialist activists manage to make their values and demands hegemonic within the sphere of civil society before they find realization through state action. See Gramsci’s discussion on the phenonemon of hegemony within civil society in Gramsci (2000, pp. 195, 205-6, 211-2, 249, 306-7, 333-4, 345). 17 A similar skepticism might partly explain why it is a good thing that the Convention for the Elimination of all Forms of Discrimination Against Women ranges over “the political, economic, social, cultural, civil or any other field” (Article 1). Part of the difficulty of this discussion turns on how to handle the distinction between what contitutes and what causes justice. See Cohen (2008, pp. 377-81). 18 I agree with Waldron (1993, pp. 25, 212) that rights generate “waves of duties” of many kinds. 19 On the role of courts in getting the political process to acknowledge and specify rigths see Gauri & Brinks (2012). 20 Rawls (1999a, pp. 99, 293-4). 21 The natural duty of justice has another part that concerns the obligation to support existing just schemes. A critic might say that this part connects only to perfect obligations. But this would be a mistake. One aspect of the duty to support just schemes, the obligation to obey just laws, is a perfect duty. But the members of a just scheme have a wider, imperfect obligation to actively engage in activities that help keep the just arrangements alive, such as voting (when it is not legally mandatory), participating in political parties, public debates, etc. 22 For elucidation and exploration of the category of “dynamic duties,” see Gilabert (2009; 2011b). 23 Shue (1988); Gilabert (2010). 24 Furthermore, institutional structures sometimes create certain roles, and thus give rise to specific interests and responsibilities (Leif Wenar, “Justice and Charity. Rawls, Roles, and Rights”—Talk delivered in the wokshop “Justice and Beneficence.” Princeton University, 9 November 2012). 25 These arrangements would include certain conventions (including those of language). These are of course, in one sense of the term, “institutional facts.” But I am here focusing on more formalized institutions whose rules are shaped and applied in a way that involves top-down command, without requiring the direct consent and control on the part of (at least some of) their subjects when they are applied. 26 For a historical study of the emergence of this idea, from Babeuf to Rawls (and their surrounding political contexts), see Fleischacker (2004, ch. 3). See also Miller (1999, ch. 1). Miller suggests that socialist challenges to capitalism played an important role in the emergence of the contemporary idea of “social justice” (p. 3). On socialist justice, see Gilabert (2015). 27 Nagel (2005). 28 Cohen & Sabel (2006); Sangiovanni (2007); Miller (2010). 29 Just as we can recognize agent-neutral besides agent-relative duties in the case of human rights, we can acknowledge both kinds of duties in the case of some egalitarian claims. See Buchanan (2004); Caney (2011); Gilabert (2012). For a different, “practical” characterization of human rights that does not rely on a humanist approach see Beitz (2009). Gilabert (2011a; 2013) argue that the insights in such a view can, and should, be combined with the humanist approach.   35                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                           30 The problem of the imperfection of duties in fact involves many possibilities depending on what aspect of a duty we focus on. The difficulties may be to identify the duties’ corresponding (a) agents, (b) acts or omissions, (c) beneficiaries, or (d) circumstances of application. 31 For other discussions on claimability see the specific proposal by O’Neill (1996), and the criticisms to it by Sen, (2004) and Ashford (2007). 32 This does not involve obliterating the distinctions between different kinds of duties of justice (negative and positive, general and associative, and the different varieties of each). They can and should all be articulated. The key point is that their mutual relations become an explicit and necessary target of discussion. 33 Cohen (2008, pp. 289-90 n.14) reports Joseph Raz’s puzzlement on this score. Some authors claim that the reference to justice does not add anything fundamental to a full account of moral duties, and that it is in fact wholly derivative. See Kagan (1998, pp. 176-7) and Buchanan (1987, pp. 574-5). 34 It also does not obliterate (and in fact invites the grasp of) different reasons of justice. See note 32 (and surrounding text). 35 Thus, Peter Singer construes the positive duty to help reduce global poverty as a matter of beneficence (on the basis of the famous analogy with the duty to rescue a child drowning in a shallow pond). See Singer (1972). But we can construe this positive duty as a demand of justice. We could then preempt the common reaction (for example by officials of governments of wealthy nations) that attending to this duty must wait until other, more stringent demands of justice have been taken care of first. 36 Forst (2012, p. 4). 37 I owe this example to Peter Singer (who does not, however, support my account of the distinction between justice and beneficence). 38 I think that this should include recognizing a right to participate in the political regulation of practices of production and distribution. For this important point see Forst (2012,p. 4). work_be7dyhrxy5dgplp3kindr5exda ---- Microsoft Word - Jenkins (2017) Setting energy justice apart from the crowd.docx Setting energy justice apart from the crowd: lessons from  environmental and climate justice Article (Accepted Version) http://sro.sussex.ac.uk Jenkins, Kirsten (2018) Setting energy justice apart from the crowd: lessons from environmental and climate justice. Energy Research and Social Science, 39. pp. 117-121. ISSN 2214-6296 This version is available from Sussex Research Online: http://sro.sussex.ac.uk/id/eprint/71448/ This document is made available in accordance with publisher policies and may differ from the published version or from the version of record. If you wish to cite this item you are advised to consult the publisher’s version. Please see the URL above for details on accessing the published version. Copyright and reuse: Sussex Research Online is a digital repository of the research output of the University. Copyright and all moral rights to the version of the paper presented here belong to the individual author(s) and/or other copyright owners. To the extent reasonable and practicable, the material made available in SRO has been checked for eligibility before being made available. Copies of full text items generally can be reproduced, displayed or performed and given to third parties in any format or medium for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-profit purposes without prior permission or charge, provided that the authors, title and full bibliographic details are credited, a hyperlink and/or URL is given for the original metadata page and the content is not changed in any way. http://sro.sussex.ac.uk/ 1 “Setting energy justice apart from the crowd: Lessons from environmental and climate justice” Abstract The continuation and exacerbation of many environmental failures illustrate that environmental and climate justice’s influence on decision-making is not being systematically effective, giving rise to a renewed emphasis on finding new, more focused, justice models. This includes the energy justice concept, which has received ready and growing success. Yet for energy justice, a key question keeps arising: what does it add that environmental and climate justice cannot? To answer this question this perspective outlines the origins, successes and failures of the environmental and climate justice concepts, with a view to both distinguishing the energy justice field, and providing cautionary tales for it. It then outlines three points of departure, which it argues increases the opportunity of success for the energy justice concept: (1) “bounding out”, (2) non-anti-establishment pasts and (3) methodological strength. This paper exists to stimulate debate. Key Words: energy justice; environmental justice; climate justice; equity Highlights • We need to distinguish environmental, climate and energy justice contributions • The environmental justice agenda has had limited pervasive impact beyond the grassroots level • Climate justice is too late and too complicated to tackle • The energy justice concept provides a more focused means to tackle injustices with environmental and climate knock-ons 2 1 Introduction In terms of academic airtime, the energy justice concept has achieved rapid success. Although its roots extend further back, since its first use as a policy-oriented term by McCauley et al. in 2013 energy justice scholarship has emerged with regards to whole-systems, energy policy-making, consumption and mobility as prominent themes amongst myriad others (Jenkins et al. 2017a). Aiding the rapid development of this literature, there have been two special issues with “energy justice” in their title, one in Energy Policy (Jenkins et al. 2017a) and one in Energy Research & Social Science (Simcock and Mullen 2016). Yet despite this apparent success key questions continue to emerge within the academic conference circuit: how is the debate on energy justice substantively different from environmental and climate justice? Is it the same thing labelled in a different way? Is the “energy only” focus reductionary? And what can it deliver that environmental and climate justice failed to? As one of innumerate examples from the literature, does the application of the energy justice concept to climate issues by Sovacool et al. (2016) illustrate overlap, or demonstrate something more productive? This perspective paper makes a first step towards answering these questions. The paper begins by outlining origins, successes and failures of the environmental and climate justice concepts, with a view to both distinguishing the energy justice field, and providing cautionary tales for it. It then outlines three points of departure, which it argues increase the opportunity of success for the energy justice concept: (1) “bounding out”, (2) non-anti-establishment pasts and (3) methodological strength. This paper exists to stimulate debate. 2 Successes and failures of the environmental and climate justice movements The following paragraphs introduce the environmental and climate justice literatures and begin to build the case for energy justice as a more manageable approach with beneficial environmental and climate knock-ons. 2.1 Environmental justice Environmental justice is commonly defined as the distribution of environmental hazards and access to all natural resources; it includes equal protection from burdens, meaningful involvement in decisions, and fair treatment in access to benefits (see Sovacool and Dworkin 2015; Hofrichter 1993; Schlosberg 1999; Cole 3 and Foster 2000). The environmental justice movement emerged in 1970s North America as a response to the unequal distribution of environmental ills – pollution and waste facilities, for example – alongside the risks associated with them, which tended to be inequitably borne by poor black/minority ethnic Americans (Davies 2006; Williams 1999). Thus it manifests as a concern for “fair treatment and meaningful involvement of all people regardless of race, colour, national origin or income with respect to the development, implementation and enforcement of environmental laws, regulations and policies” (Bass 1998: 83). Through a focus on alerting, educating and mobilising the public to the unequal distribution and environmental risks and benefits, and also on ensuring the meaningful participation of affected communities in decision-making, it represents distributive and procedural justice concerns (Evans and Phelan 2016). Initially, environmental justice complaints focused on local, activism-led, community-oriented means of ensuring the just distribution of toxic burdens; a distributionally-based form of environmental justice inquiry that could be operationalised and measured on a local scale (Holifield et al. 2009). Since its inception, however, many authors have noted that the concept of environmental justice has grown both substantively and theoretically (Bevc et al. 2007; Pulido 1996; Walker 2009; Schlosberg 2013). Williams (1999) illustrates, for example, that federal governments established policies to protect against future inequity in environmental decisions, recognising not just local, but also national impacts of noxious facilities. Thus the geographical scale of application within the Unites States changed. In this regard, Agyeman and Evans (2004) identify two inter-related dimensions of this form of environmental justice: (1) a local, activist level using it as a vocabulary for mobilisation, action, and political opportunity, and (2) a government level that sees environmental justice as a policy principle, stating that no public action will disproportionately disadvantage any particular social group. Further, in their review of environmental justice literature Reed and George (2011) state that whilst much research is still framed around the distribution of hazards and risk, the scope of what these risks are perceived to be has grown too. In the years following their analysis this is increasingly the case. Indeed, within the literature topics of concern range from prominent debates on toxic waste, air pollution and landfill sites, to new technology, ecological restoration, transport, health, energy, housing, access to food and forest management, amongst others (Sze and London 4 2008; Schlosberg 2013; Liu 2000; Walker 2009). Yet despite this, Hess and Ribeiro (2016) identify that energy has yet to become a major concern for environmental justice, and that injustices along the global supply chain have not yet been tackled satisfactorily. Holifield et al. (2009) also highlight a shift within the movement towards a more multi-faceted understanding of the concept, where environmental justice is increasingly used in coalition with other theories and agendas, including the capabilities approach, social movement theories, assemblages, and actor network theory. In this regard the environmental justice agenda has gradually expanded from a social movement to a policy vocabulary, and a research field in its own right (Bulkeley et al. 2013; Agyeman 2014; Walker and Bulkeley 2006). On the grounds of this expanding scope, some see the literature as flourishing, expanding, and deepening. They do so as apparent recognition of a growing international scholarship, with many instances of engagement through both activism and policy processes (although the successes of these are challenging to verify) (Chakraborty 2017). The expanding scope of environmental justice interpretations and applications are also understood by some as necessary, given that justice is an inherently complex and contested concept which will inevitably be taken to mean different things in different settings, cultures, and political arenas. Conscious of this positivity, it is therefore problematic to determine whether the environmental justice concept or movement is either a “success” or a “failure”, despite the following negative critiques. With this in mind, this paper does not prescribe a positive or negative outcome or suggest an abandonment of environmental justice work. Instead, it argues that this growth limits the material impact of environmental justice claims. Notwithstanding the widespread uptake of the topic within academia, the environmental justice agenda is widely criticised for its failure to have a pervasive impact beyond the grassroots level – the result, perhaps, of increasing diffusion of its meaning and application, and a lack of a strong conceptual core. As an illustration, Bickerstaff and Agyeman (2009) note the limited uptake of the environmental justice concept in the UK, where the environmental justice movement does not utilize the vocabulary of mobilising minority and low-income groups, and, in their words, is yet to make any significant impact on policy and decision-making. Reed and George (2011) demonstrate that despite some overseas proliferation, on the whole 5 environmental justice research remains US-centric. Heffron et al. (2015: 175) later reinforce this critique by stating that environmental justice faces two problems: (1) that the definitions are too broad and (2) that this has resulted in difficulty of translation into economics and therefore, policy formation. This perspective identifies that energy justice faces (at least) two major weaknesses. Firstly, whilst the concept has been used as a mobilizing tool, it lacks defined and recognised content—a structure or approach that can be readily applied at a range of scales in a systematic manner. Secondly, because of the way the concept has been used, it has not achieved much environmental protection or conservation. Instead, the main motivation of the movement has been the affect on less affluent areas—a concern for people, not their environment. The result, arguably, is a floundering concept, with little benefit beyond the grassroots level. 2.2 Climate justice The evolution of the climate justice concept and movement sits alongside the methodological and theoretical growth of environmental justice. Climate justice first evolved from climate change activism, where a focus on the grassroots environmental justice movement combined with concern for global climate change. The concept, or movement, began gathering pace in the 1990s, with a focus primarily on: assisting those affected by climate change; sharing the burdens and benefits of climate change; mitigation and adaptation; and reducing CO2 emissions (Lyster 2015). Goodman (2009: 509) thus describes the role of climate justice as an “interpretative frame” for the climate crisis, and a concept that addresses the “triple inequity” of mitigation, responsibility and vulnerability by (1) asking who benefits from CO2 emissions and how should they bear the burden for mitigation, (2) recognising the vast divergence in capabilities to respond to global climate change, and (3) addressing the issue of adaptation, the burdens of which are unequally focused on the world’s poor. Bulkeley et al. (2013: 915) summarise the agenda as the mobilisation of justice with respect to climate policy, and state that the concept has “provided a means through which to bring concerns for the outcomes and processes of climate policy into the same frame of analysis”. They go on to state that in contrast to the origins of environmental justice in local struggles, arguments or debates about climate justice appear predominantly at the international level (see also Lahn 2017 and Ciplet 6 and Roberts 2017). Heffron et al. (2015) point to the perceived failure of the international Kyoto Protocol for example, which triggered climate protests and calls for climate justice. The climate justice framework has, however, also been applied to nation states and cities, demonstrating national, local and international applicability (e.g. Ambrey et al. 2017, Bulkeley et al. 2013 or Zhang et al. 2017). In addition, although climate justice has predominantly concerned itself with issues of justice among and between existing and future humans (Palmer 2011), work such as that of Schneider and Lane (2006) on “inter-species equity” conceptualises its impact more widely (Sovacool et al. 2017). The challenge that climate justice is a struggling concept is, to some scholars, not going to be a welcome one. As with environmental justice, counter arguments may come as the defence that the concept is understood and used in different ways due to different understandings and manifestations of (in)justice—a perhaps understandable diversity. Moreover, some may assert that the relatively limited application of climate change policy hides its successful application in a local setting or on a smaller scale, where it may hold more promise. Indeed, you could claim that without climate justice arguments being mobilised in international and local forums, progress would have been even more phlegmatic and even more inequitable. Yet, despite this positivity, a number of authors have increasingly begun to reflect on the failures of the climate justice literature (Schlosberg and Collins 2014; Heyward and Roser 2016). The climate crisis is an all-enveloping one. Is climate justice scholarship coming too late and is it too complicated to tackle? How do we define the right to sustainable development, deal with currently untapped oil and gas reserves and the rights to them, and contend with the unequal distribution of wealth, and therefore the unequal potential to successfully adapt? No answers are on the horizon, and the multiple possibilities for change are confusing. If we consider the target to keep global average temperatures well below 2- degrees above pre-industrial levels, the mitigation of climate change is certainly already a failure (Rogelj et al. 2016). Despite some countries taking positive action, major global contributors have yet to sanction climate change agreements. At the end of March 2017, 141 of 197 member countries had ratified the Paris Accord that was adopted in 2015 (Marquardt 2017). The United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change now puts this total at 168 (UNFCCC 2017). The United States, one 7 of the largest global CO2 producers, shows a recent and potentially extremely damaging trend in climate change policy with a proposed move to withdraw from the agreement (that said, its national policies may nevertheless still result in significant CO2 reductions). This limited success of the climate justice movement is well documented through negotiations at the UNFCCC COP meetings (see Goodman 2009 for a comprehensive history) as well as the continued steady increase in CO2 emissions (Rogelj et al. 2016). Climate justice presents what Goodman (2009) describes as a “proactive ideological agenda”, arguing, in some cases, for the need to curtail global growth rates in order to get runaway climate change under control. The questions of “responsibility” this raises (who does what and for whose benefit?) are contentious for two main reasons. First, continued inadequacy of action is increasing the potential for profound loss from climate impacts. Secondly, the increasing urgency of increasing emissions and the shifting locus of emissions has put pressure on countries already facing continued human development challenges (Klinsky 2015). The result is that few are taking responsibility on a large enough scale and that as an outcome adaptive resilience is becoming more critical. There is also a role for climate justice through legal cases. Abate (2016) describes the evolution of “atmospheric trust litigation” (ATL) in the United States (US), where ATL targets government entities and uses a “public trust” doctrine to challenge the government’s environmental stewardship responsibilities. The headline case in the US is “Kelsey Cascadia Rose Juliana et al. v. United States of America et al.” (2016), where a group of plaintiffs filed action against the US, the then President, Barack Obama and several executive agencies for their failure to phase out fossil fuel exploitation and avert environmental catastrophe. Recently, a 9-year old girl in India has filed a lawsuit against the Indian government for failing to take action on climate change. In the end, however, these discussions have neither achieved internal coherence on the purpose and form of the climate justice concept, nor achieved climate justice for any particular individuals or groups. Moreover, where positive examples do occur, they remain small scale and too disparate to face larger, immediate climate challenges and risks. Thus, this perspective argues that a bright future for fast, successful climate justice action is clouding over, and a more manageable framing of the challenge is required. 8 3 Energy justice: Three explanations for difference The continuation and exacerbation of many environmental failures illustrate that environmental and climate justice’s influence on decision-making is not effective enough. These failures have manifested as an increasing drive to find new, more focused, justice models, including those centered on energy issues. One result is the energy justice concept. Against the background of the environmental and climate justice literatures and sharing the same basic philosophy, energy justice aims ‘to provide all individuals, across all areas, with safe, affordable and sustainable energy’ (McCauley et al. 2013: 1). It does so with a framework informed by the environmental justice movement, including attention to the core tenets of distributional justice, procedural justice and justice as recognition. As identified by Sovacool and Dworkin (2015), this means that energy justice exists as a conceptual tool for uniting usually distinct justice concerns, an analytical tool for energy researchers seeking to understand how values are embedded in energy systems or resolve their neglect and, importantly, a decision-making tool that can help energy planners make more considered energy choices. It is necessary, at this stage, to acknowledge the scope of the concept. Evidently, the focus of environmental, climate and energy justice are different. Energy justice is concerned with energy systems, whereas climate justice and environmental justice extend beyond this, including both energy and non-energy sources of (in)justice. Whilst energy justice can, in some cases, capture non-energy impacts of projects such as local biodiversity impacts of new facilities (Goldthau and Sovacool 2012), this is undoubtedly on a smaller scale. Thus, the argument here is not that that energy justice is a superior alternative to environmental and climate justice, but instead, that it is a more strategically impactful one. Heffron and McCauley (2017: 663) state that “energy justice has the opportunity to avoid the pitfalls of environmental and climate justice scholarship and build a more solid and lasting foundation to its core meaning and value”. Further, Hernández (2016: 152) adds “as both a social and environmental issue, the intersection of energy and poverty presents untapped and timely possibilities for seeking justice and equity for those sacrificed and sacrificing vis-à-vis energy”. As it is specifically focused on energy issues, the energy justice frame possesses more traction (by several metrics) than the other approaches. It is a rapidly applicable 9 approach that can make more meaningful progress. By building the argument that energy justice is a tighter and more manageable justice framing that already comes with a clear, definable content, this article now asks why the resultant energy justice concept is better placed to do this. 3.1 “Bounding out” So far, this perspective has argued that one of the challenges and therefore potential failings of the environmental and climate justice movement is their breadth and lack of clearly defined content. The expanding scope of environmental justice displays a diffusion of meaning, and the concept is not readily applied globally. Climate justice considers the rights of every global individual both now and in the future, for both known and unforeseen injustices. In both cases the result is concepts too discursively diverse to tackle. Energy justice on the other hand, provides a means of focusing our efforts, with beneficial environmental and climate justice knock-ons. Bickerstaff et al. (2013: 2), identify that the energy justice concept “provides a way of ‘bounding’ and separating out energy concerns from the wider range of topics addressed within both environmental and climate justice campaigning”. Energy justice does this by focusing on each stage of the whole energy system, encompassing resource mining through to waste management and energy consumption (Jenkins et al. 2014, 2016). Thus, it provides a combination of the social science account of energy (policy) with its natural science counterpart (systems) (Jenkins et al. 2014; Jenkins et al. 2016). This is a positive. Such an approach makes justice and equity questions understandable to people by breaking them into smaller chunks. At each stage of the energy system – resource mining or energy production, for example – energy justice can engage with local, regional and national justice questions. If each systems component is combined with its fellows, energy justice then provides a global lens through which to assess our energy infrastructure. Whilst it is easy to turn ones eyes from insurmountable, diffuse challenges such as climate justice, an energy systems justice focus brings them closer and makes them more understandable. After that, the challenge becomes one of how we discuss, negotiate and implement what will likely be transnational energy justice claims. 10 3.2 Non-activist past Although only in passing, Heffron et al. (2015) and Jenkins et al. (2016) allude to the strength of energy justice because of its “non-activist past”, which gives it a clearly defined content and approach. While referenced in principle during the environmental justice movement by non-academics, and having emerged indirectly from decades of activist campaigning for environmental and climate justice, energy justice has principally been developed as an academic concept. Indeed, apart from one larger network in the United States (The Energy Justice Network: www.energyjustice.net) and more recently, the UK-based group Global Justice Now (www.globaljustice.org.uk), it is not a term that is frequently and explicitly used in activist discourse. This lack of an anti-establishment past opens the door for significant contributions to mainstream policy-making (Jenkins et al. 2016). Energy justice does so by overcoming what may be identified as the “naïve” approaches of environmental and climate justice – the presumption that society would support their ideals (Heffron and McCauley 2017) – focusing instead on embedding justice in policy. This “top-down” methodology offers the potential for a refined “practice” framework rather than disparate grassroots call, although it is also acknowledged that top-down approaches present their own pitfalls. This statement comes with the primary caveat that we must not negate the importance of activism entirely. It seems dangerous and somewhat technocratic to make the assumption that change takes place most effectively or entirely without it. Indeed, some may highlight circumstances and case studies when policy actors have only paid attention to questions justice when society and broader political processes have demanded it. Further, the idea of justice as recognition is particularly rooted in the idea of those who are discriminated against, de-valued and stigmatized—groups most easily identified as those making claims and those that must be revealed in policy-decision making. Nonetheless, the presence of a strong policy-oriented focus provides opportunity for more rapid, systematic implementation. In tandem, activist discourses retain the important role of assessing and directing energy policy (Jenkins et al. 2017b). 3.3 Methodological approach As documented by Jenkins et al. (2017a), a number of different approaches have emerged to exploring the social dimensions of energy supply and use (see Day 11 and Walker 2013; Day et al. 2016). Heffron et al. (2015) sought to quantify energy justice, for example. A recent special issue in the journal Energy Policy delivered papers oriented towards energy justice scholarship as normative, change-driven and policy focused, questioning which methods are needed for assessing the prevalence of injustices and remediating them. The papers within delivered approaches to energy justice that incorporated the novel, practice-oriented approaches of participatory energy budgeting (Capaccioli et al. 2017), odds ratio analysis (Liljenfeldt and Pettersson 2017), economizing energy justice through electricity equity tariffs (Palavicino and Ureta 2017) and policy assessments (Healy and Barry 2017), alongside qualitative approaches using semi-structured interviews (Jenkins et al. 2017b) – thus gaining insight from across the academic disciplines. The outcome is an early set of tools that can take energy justice past academic discourse to practical action. Using the framework of Miller et al. (2015), the result is an energy justice concept that can be implemented throughout (1) the practices and techniques through which potential energy futures are envisioned, analysed, modelled where required, and evaluated, (2) the forums and methods for deliberating, debating, and making energy choices, and (3) the institutions for fashioning, operating, and regulating new energy systems. Of course, the claim that energy justice can be implemented through a variety of techniques, methods and institutional arrangements has limitations. Due to the recent emergence of the concept, there is little empirical evidence of its traction on energy decision-making. Instead, this evaluation is made on the basis of the early existence of these approaches and their early application to date as well as political interest in the topic area. Additionally, it is necessary to recognise that even with ‘clean cut’, well-planned tools, energy justice is likely to encounter contested, tricky and political dilemmas and resistances. As above, this institutionalised view of decision-making processes and change is subject to assessment from both activist groups and wider society. Nonetheless, the presence of and growing literature around these approaches shows intention not just to discuss, but to apply justice concepts. 4 Conclusions This paper concludes, in part, that energy justice provides a lens through which we can begin to tackle related environmental and climate justice issues more 12 effectively. Outlining the contribution of energy justice beyond this broad claim, this paper has established that there are (at least) three distinguishing aspects of energy justice, which set the concept and movement apart from the environmental and climate justice scholarship and aid its potential success. Energy justice is (1) more targeted in its topic of concern and systems focus, and therefore has increased potential for policy uptake, (2) unlike environmental and climate justice, is not the outcome of anti-establishment social movements, and (3) is backed by a strong methodological tradition which shows a range of both academic and policy-relevant applications. Each of these factors increases its potential for widespread applications. By implication, there should be a continued and fervent increase in energy justice scholarship and application. Yet, recognising the limitations of this piece, we also require more reflexivity across the disciplines. Outside of the statements made in this paper, there have been few attempts to distinguish this scholarship and to understand and translate lessons across the concepts (Heffron and McCauley 2017). Whilst they are united by a concern for justice, they are segregated into academic silos. Thus, this paper closes with a call for both conceptual and empirical accounts of contrast and corroboration. The result, it is hoped, will be refined and practically applicable concepts ready to face the complex challenges of justice in an ever-changing environmental, energy and climate landscape. References Abate RS (2016) ‘Climate justice: case studies in global and regional governance challenges’, Faculty Books and Book Contributions 34: 543-570 Agyeman J (2014) ‘Global environmental justice or Le droit au monde?’, Geoforum 54: 236- 238 Agyeman J and Evans B (2004) ‘’Just Sustainability’: The emerging discourse of environmental justice in Britain?’, The Geographical Journal 170(2): 115-164 Alvial-Palavicino C and Ureta S (2017) ‘Economizing justice: Turning equity claims into lower energy tariffs in Chile’, Energy Policy 105: 642-647 Ambrey C, Byrne J, Matthews T, Davison A, Portanger C and Lo A (2017) ‘Cultivating climate justice: Green infrastructure and suburban disadvantage in Australia’, Applied Geography 89: 52-60 Bass R (1998) ‘Evaluating environmental justice under the national environmental policy act’, Environmental Impact Assessment Review 18(1): 83-92 Bevc CA, Brent K M and Picou SJ (2007) ‘Environmental justice and toxic exposure: towards a spatial model of physical health and psychological well-being’, Social Science Research 36(1): 48–67 13 Bickerstaff K and Agyeman J (2009) ‘Assembling Justice Spaces: The Scalar Politics of Environmental Justice in North-east England’, Antipode 41(4): 781-806 Bickerstaff K, Walker G and Bulkeley H (2013) ‘Energy justice in a changing climate: social equity and low-carbon energy, Zed Books, London Bulkeley H, Carmin J, Broto VC, Edwards GAS, and Fuller S (2013) ‘Climate justice and global cities: mapping the emerging discourses’, Global Environmental Change 23(5): 914-925 Capaccioli A, Poderi G, Bettega M and D’Andrea (2017) ‘Exploring participatory energy budgeting as a policy instrument to foster energy justice’, Energy Policy 107: 621-630 Chakraborty J (2017) ‘Focus on environmental justice: new directions in international research’, Environmental Research Letters 12(3): 1-4. Ciplet D. and Roberts JT (2017) Climate change and the transition to neoliberal environmental governance’, Global Environmental Change 46: 148-156 Cole LW and Foster SR (2000) ‘From the ground up: environmental racism and the rise of the environmental justice movement’, New York University Press Davies A (2006) ‘Environmental justice as subtext or omission: examining discourses of anti- incineration campaigns in Ireland’, Geoforum 37: 708-724 Day R and Walker G (2013) ‘Household energy vulnerability as “assemblage”’ in Bickerstaff K, Walker G, and Bulkeley H (2013) ‘Energy justice in a changing climate: social equity and low-carbon energy’, Zed Books, London (Chapter 1) Day R, Walker G and Simcock N (2016) ‘Conceptualising energy use and energy poverty using a capabilities framework’, Energy Policy 93: 255-264 Evans G and Phelan L (2016) ‘Transition to a post-carbon society: Linking environmental justice and just transitions’, Energy Policy 99: 329-339 Goldthau A and Sovacool KB (2012) ‘The Uniqueness of the Energy Security, Justice, and Governance Problem’, Energy Policy 41: 232-240 Goodman J (2009) ‘From Global Justice to Climate Justice? Justice Ecologism in an Era of Global Warming’, New Political Science 31(4): 499-514 Healy N and Barry J (2017) ‘Politicizing energy justice and energy systems transition: Fossil fuel divestment and a “just transition”’, Energy Policy 108: 451-459 Heffron R and McCauley D (2017) ‘The concept of energy justice across the disciplines’, Energy Policy 105: 658-667 Heffron RJ, McCauley D and Sovacool BK (2015) ‘Resolving society’s energy trilemma through the energy justice metric’, Energy Policy 87: 168-176 Hernánde D (2015) ‘Sacrifice along the energy continuum: A call for energy justice’, Environmental Justice 8(4): 151-156 Hess CEE and Ribeiro WC (2016) ‘Energy and environmental justice: Closing the gap’, Environmental Justice 9(5): 153-158 Heyward and Roser (Eds.) 2016 ‘Climate justice in a non-ideal world’, Oxford University Press Hofrichter R (Ed.) (1993) ‘Toxic Struggles: The Theory and Practice of Environmental Justice’, New Society, Philadelphia Holifield R, Porter M and Walker G (2009) ‘Introduction Spaces of Environmental Justice: Frameworks for Critical Engagement’, Antipode 41(4): 591-612 Jenkins K, McCauley D and Forman A (2017a) ‘Energy justice: a policy approach’, Energy Policy 105: 631-634 Jenkins K, McCauley D, and Warren CR (2017b) ‘Attributing responsibility for energy justice: A case study of the Hinkley Point Nuclear Complex’, Energy Policy 108: 836-843 14 Jenkins K, McCauley D, Heffron R J, Stephan H and Rehner R (2016) ‘Energy justice: A conceptual review’, Energy Research and Social Science 11: 174-182 Jenkins K, McCauley D, Heffron RJ and Stephan H (2014) 'Energy justice, a whole systems approach', Queen's Political Review 29(2): 74-87 Kelsey Cascadia Rose Juliana et al., (Plaintiffs) v. United States of America et al. (Defendants) (2016) Case 6:15-cv-01517-TC Document 83 Klinsky S (2015) ‘Transitional justice in the climate context? Discussion paper”, Climate Strategies: 1-11 Lahn B (2017) ‘In the light of equity and science: scientific expertise and climate justice after Paris’, International Environmental Agreements: Politics, Law and Economics 1-15. Liljenfeldt J and Pettersson O (2017) ‘Distributional justice in Swedish wind power development – An odds ration analysis of windmill localization and local residents’ socio-economic characteristics’, Energy Policy 105: 648-657 Liu F (2000) ‘Environmental Justice Analysis: Theories, Methods and Practice’, CRC Press Textbook Lyster R (2015) ‘Climate Justice and Disaster Law’. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK Marquardt J (2017) ‘Conceptualizing power in multi-level climate governance’, Journal of Cleaner Production 154: 167-175 McCauley D, Heffron R, Stephan H and Jenkins K (2013) 'Advancing Energy Justice: The Triumvirate of Tenets', International Energy Law Review 32(3): 107-110 Miller CA, Richter J and Jason O’Leary (2015) ‘Socio-energy systems design: A policy framework for energy transitions’, Energy Research and Social Science 6: 29-40 Palmer C (2011) ‘Does Nature Matter? The Place of the Nonhuman in the Ethics of Climate Change. The Ethics of Global Climate Change’, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK, 272–291 Pulido L (1996) ‘A critical review of the methodology of environmental racism research’, Antipode 28(2): 142-159 Reed GM and George C (2011) ‘Where in the world is environmental justice?’, Progress in Human Geography 35(6): 835-842 Rogelj J, den Elzen M, Hohne N, Fransen T, Fekete H, Winkler H, Schaeffer R, Sha F, Riahi K and Meinshausen M (2016) ‘Paris Agreement climate proposals need to boost to keep warming well below 2 °C’, Nature Perspectives 534: 631-639 Schlosberg D (1999) ‘Environmental justice and the new pluralism: the challenge of difference for Environmentalism’, Oxford University Press world’, UCT Press, South Africa Schlosberg D (2013) ‘Theorising Environmental Justice: The Expanding Sphere of a Discourse’, Environmental Politics 22(1): 37-55 Schlosberg D and Collins LB (2014) ‘From environmental to climate justice: climate change and the discourse of environmental justice’, WIREs Climate Change 5(3): 359-374 Schneider SH and Lane J (2006) ‘Dangers and thresholds in climate change and the implications for justice. Fairness in adaptation to climate change’. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, 23–51 Simcock N and Mullen C (2016) ‘Energy demand for everyday mobility and domestic life: Exploring the justice implications’, Energy Research and Social Science 18: 1-6 Sovacool BK and Dworkin MH (2015) ‘Energy Justice: Conceptual Insights and 15 Practical Applications’, Applied Energy 142: 435-444 Sovacool BK, Burke M, Baker L, Kotikalapudi CK, and Wlokas H (2017) ‘New conceptual frameworks for energy justice”, Energy Policy 105: 677-691 Sovacool BK, Heffron RJ, McCauley D and Goldthau A (2016) ‘Energy decisions reframed as justice and ethical concerns’, Nature Energy 1: 1-6 Sze J and London JK (2008) ‘Environmental Justice at a Crossroads’, Sociology Compass 2(4): 1331-1354 UNFCCC (2017) ‘Paris Agreement – Status of Ratification’, United Nations Framework Convention of Climate Change. Available online. Accessed on 6th June 2017 http://unfccc.int/paris_agreement/items/9444.php Walker G (2009) ‘Beyond Distribution and Proximity: Exploring the Multiple Spatialities of Environmental Justice’, Antipode 41(4): 614-636 Walker G and Bulkeley H (2006) ‘Geographies of Environmental Justice’, Geoforum 37: 655-659 Williams WR (1999) ‘Environmental injustice in America and its politics of scale’, Political Geography 18: 49-73 Zhang Y, Chao Q, Zheng Q and Huang L (2017) ‘The withdrawal of the U.S. from the Paris Agreement and its impact on global climate change governance’, Advances in Climate Change Research. In Press work_beohta2ozzbtrnzj4vnsiqdvxy ---- Geogr. Helv., 75, 403–414, 2020 https://doi.org/10.5194/gh-75-403-2020 © Author(s) 2020. This work is distributed under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 License. su p p o rt e d b y S pecialE dition S O C IA L G E O G R A P H Y Between divine and social justice: emerging climate-justice narratives in Latin American socio-environmental struggles Celia Ruiz-de-Oña Plaza Centre for Multidisciplinary Research on Chiapas and the Southern Border (CIMSUR), National Autonomous University of Mexico (UNAM), San Cristóbal de Las Casas, Chiapas, Mexico Correspondence: Celia Ruiz-de-Oña Plaza (celiardo@unam.mx) Received: 30 December 2019 – Revised: 9 August 2020 – Accepted: 12 October 2020 – Published: 2 December 2020 Abstract. This exploratory study traces the emergence of climate justice claims linked to narratives of Latin American social movements for the defence of life and territory. I argue that in post-colonial settings, religious and historical injustices and socio-cultural factors act as constitutive elements of environmental and climate justice understandings which are grounded in territories immersed in neo-extractivism conflicts. Environmen- tal and climate justice conceptualizations have overlooked the religious fact present in many Latin American socio-environmental movements. As a result, the intertwined notions of divine justice and social justice are unacknowledged. To illustrate this claim, I examine socio-environmental and climate justice claims in a cross- border region between Guatemala and Chiapas. This region has a common ethnic background but divergent historical trajectories across the border. Diverse nuances and intensities adopted by environmental and climate justice practices and narratives on both sides of the border are examined. The case study reveals the importance of religion as a force for collective action and as a channel for the promotion of place-based notions of climate justice. The text calls for the examination of the religious factor, in its multiple expressions, in the theories of climate and environmental justice. 1 Introduction Socio-environmental struggles in Latin America are, in many cases, sustained by a formal religious faith or by adaptations of ancestral world views (Lorentzen and Salvador, 2006). However, as Kirmani (2008) has noted, the religious ele- ment is often omitted when studying social movements. The same is true of the environmental-justice literature. In con- trast, the link between religion and climate change – and more broadly, between religion and environmentalism – is increasingly addressed in the environmental-humanities field (Jenkins, 2017) as well as in media and religious studies (Bergmann, 2009; Gottlieb, 2010). Thus, the diverse litera- ture that does address the religious element confirms that, religion as a social institution plays a key role in instigat- ing collective action and issuing justice claims based upon a spiritual and sacred notion of nature (Haluza-DeLay, 2014). That literature also examines the different approaches taken by diverse faiths when confronting environmental devasta- tion and climate change. Among the elements problematized in that literature are religious dogma, structure, organiza- tion, and conceptions of deity and human nature (Gerten and Bergmann, 2011; Veldman et al., 2013). However, this body of research is not connected, at present, to the environmental and climate-justice conceptualizations. Meanwhile, in the social and political sphere, claims for climate justice are increasingly shaped by dogmas of the faiths that serve social movements as channels of dissemina- tion and sources of motivation. A notable example of those dogmas is liberation theology, of Catholic orientation (Bel- ing and Vanhulst, 2019). Recent research into the influence of such dogmas appears to have been triggered by the debate surrounding the papal encyclical Laudato si’ (published in 2015), which calls emphatically for stronger action against climate change. It prompts for a more integrative view of climate justice: one that moves away from carbon issues Published by Copernicus Publications for the Geographisch-Ethnographische Gesellschaft Zürich & Association Suisse de Géographie. 404 C. Ruiz-de-Oña Plaza: Between divine and social justice: emerging climate-justice narratives in Latin America (Honty, 2011) and effectively links climate to cultural and symbolic factors (including those that derive from religion). However, local congregations of different faiths can vary markedly in how they view climate-justice issues and act upon them in the light of their respective religious declara- tions. For example, does their understanding of those decla- rations impel them to action, or not? What is the relevance of their faiths to the configuration of placed-based notions of environmental and climate justice? What different expres- sions do those notions take, and what are the determining factors for this differentiation? In what way are environmen- tal and climate issues being linked in specific territories? And what narratives are the people building? Exploring these questions can contribute to broadening and diversifying the notions of environmental and climate justice. To illustrate this, I examine socio-environmental and climate justice claims in a cross-border region between Guatemala and Chiapas: the southwestern segment of the 1000 km border strip, in the Mam ethnic territories bordering the Tacaná volcano area (see Fig. 1). This region has a com- mon ethnic background but divergent historical trajectories across the border. Religion occupies a central role as an orga- nizing institution in social life, as well as in resistance strug- gles. There are several religious faiths present on both sides of the border (see Fig. 1). However, not all of them lead to environmental anti-capitalist activism. Those involved with liberation theology are configuring demands for environmen- tal justice which are conceived as struggles for the defence of territory and for the right to political autonomy of indigenous peoples. Within this framework, a place-based notion of en- vironmental justice is constructed, one that is anchored in socio-environmental conflicts and rooted in cultural ways of understanding the territory. In recent times, mentions of climate change in connection with the impacts of neo-extractivism are increasingly com- mon in the narratives of socio-environmental movements op- erating in this cross-border region. The article looks at two socio-environmental movements: the Movement for the De- fence of Life and Territory (MODEVITE), on the Mexican side (Table 1), and the Maya Mam, Te Txe Chman council, on the Guatemalan side (Table 2). I hypothesize that the religious – primarily, but not exclu- sively, liberation theology – is driving the emergence of cli- mate justice narratives in these socio-environmental move- ments, hand in hand with the encyclical Laudato si’. From here, incipient claims of climate justice linked to territory, culture, and politics are arising. The case of this cross-border region illustrates this process. On both sides of the border, the churches spread and generate awareness of climate jus- tice. However, divergent historical trajectories and the un- equal presence and action of the nation state give rise to prac- tices and narratives of religion and climate change of varying intensity across the border. In this light, the objective of this paper is to highlight the need to update and complement the literature’s present no- tions of environmental and climate justice, specifically by including elements such as religious motifs as fundamen- tal elements of future justice conceptualizations. The role of those elements might be demonstrated by treating instances where they support and interact with historical and social- justice claims in territories with a colonial legacy (Álvarez and Coolsaet, 2018). I conclude by noting that this region’s contingent particularities provide an opportunity to broaden and enrich the conceptualizations found in the literature. 2 Social movements as socio-environmental struggles in Latin American contexts: the eco-territorial turn Throughout Latin America, protests are surging in response to the social and environmental impacts of infrastructure mega-projects, the expansion of non-traditional agricultural exports, and extractive industries such as mining or hydro- electricity. In this context, impacts of climate change are in- tensifying. They are also interacting with the effects of this wave of neo-extractivism. Quite often, the resulting social mobilizations become transnational via a diverse network of 70 organizations, ranging from traditional campesino unions and indigenous groups to urban environmentalists. As the need arises, organizations in that network create ad hoc fronts to support specific struggles. At the heart of the overarching social unrest lies an ac- tive and visceral rejection of the necropolitics and necroe- conomics of the current capitalism phase (Mbembe, 2003). Sometimes known collectively as the “politics of death”, this politico-economic subjugation is particularly intense in Latin America, where it is implemented by right-wing and left- wing governments alike (Botero and Galeano, 2017). Ac- cording to African scholar Achille Mbembe, the politics of death result in human rights violations (Bastos and de León, 2014; Navarro, 2013; Sosa and Camey-Huz, 2015), as well as ecological devastation and the exclusion of entire popula- tions that are considered superfluous to the production sys- tem (Mbembe, 2003). Social movements are responding to this context by recon- figuring themselves under the banner of socio-environmental struggles. These movements call for political autonomy, rad- ical democracy, the right to be consulted, and the right to de- cide the destinies of their own territories. A common narra- tive unifies socio-environmental struggles of many forms and tendencies under the banner of the defence of life and terri- tory. The critical axis of this narrative is constructed against hegemonic territorialities that neglect other forms of being, in favour of a new relationship between the non-human and the human world. That relationship includes the emergence of new ontologies of being more than human (de la Cadena, 2010; Escobar, 2014), along with other rationalities not based on the neoliberal rationale. Also included is the articulation of a range of actors across different scales of collective ac- Geogr. Helv., 75, 403–414, 2020 https://doi.org/10.5194/gh-75-403-2020 C. Ruiz-de-Oña Plaza: Between divine and social justice: emerging climate-justice narratives in Latin America 405 Table 1. Characteristics of the Movement for the Defence of Life and Territory (MODEVITE): Chiapas. Origin Consolidated during the year 2011, MODEVITE is a coalition of groups that form a social movement based on the liberation theology of Pueblo Creyente (Believing People) of the diocese of San Cristóbal. Composition and location Members belong to three ethnic groups – Tseltal, Tsotsil, and Cho‘l peoples – in 13 municipalities in the Lacan- don Jungle and the highlands of Chiapas. MODEVITE has a strong presence among the Catholic Comunidades de Base Eclesiales (base communities of Catholic groups that are part of the parish churches) located at the southern border with Guatemala, among a population that in the past had indigenous ancestry. Subsequently, the Mexican state’s long-term process of acculturation caused the loss of indigenous identities. Context of emergence Communities invaded by gangs involved in illegal migration, prostitution, drug trafficking, and radical violence, particularly against women. Mode of operation and religious affiliation Catholic faith aligned with liberation theology in the preferential option for the poor. The parish churches affiliated with MODEVITE act as nodes of an extensive territorial network that operates through different working committees. The underlying and unifying task of the committees is to understand their shared reality through the study and reinterpretation of the Bible from an indigenous and subaltern perspective. Problems attended MODEVITE focuses on a mix of local social problems caused by the above-mentioned context of violence: the struggle against mining and transnational energy companies and the rejection of traditional political forces allied with paramilitary bodies. Justice claims MODEVITE focuses on issues such as violence, instability, ungovernability, and alcoholism, along with threats to the territories from mining, oil production, hydroelectric installations, and infrastructure mega-projects that damage sacred sites, “mother earth”, and the communities. Collective action Political action against political parties and corruption, and to promote community governments in each of the 11 municipalities as an exercise of their right to self-determination (MODEVITE, Final Communiqué of the Pilgrimage, 2016). MODEVITE seeks to establish a new political arena based on a radical democratic exercise. Human–nature relationships Action aimed at the recovery and rebuilding of a sense of belonging to nature and a collective unity based on a newly redefined indigenous identity. Source: prepared by the author based on dispatches, news, and posts from https://modevite.wordpress.com/2019/08/21/comunicados/ (last access: 15 August 2020) and https://sipaz.wordpress.com/2019/08/21/chiapas-megaperegrinacion-del-movimiento-en-defensa-de-la-vida-y-del-territorio-modevite-en-tuxtla-gutierrez/ (last access: 15 August 2020). tion. Regarding science, this new relationship would promote alternatives to the dominant narratives of scientificism. In summary, this relationship calls for a new language of val- orization that would both supersede the coloniality of knowl- edge (Mignolo and Escobar, 2013) and create new meanings that amplify the dimensions of life instead of reducing it to a narrow productivity rationale. That rationale emphasizes the politics of racialization, as well as the collective transgen- erational psychological and subjective marks of submission still operating in post-colonial contexts (Álvarez and Cool- saet, 2018). In territories where the colonial legacy left an im- print of a sense of subjugation, psychological processes can- not be detached from the structural: both are relevant to un- derstanding how socio-environmental struggles emerge and unfold. Coloniality anchors a racial ideology in the psycho- logical structure of the oppressed peoples who have been tar- gets of domination strategies in Latin America (Grosfoguel, 2011). Therefore, the transformation of objective conditions is, by itself, as insufficient as the transformation of only the subjective sphere (Álvarez and Coolsaet 2018). The innovative collective action described above has been labelled the “eco-territorial turn” – a term coined by a group of Latin American socio-environmental thinkers (Alimonda, 2011; Leff, 2014; Svampa, 2019). The territory is understood as the result of the interaction of its environmental, mate- rial, social, cultural, and symbolic dimensions. Of these, the spiritual/religious dimension is often highlighted in territo- ries with an indigenous presence (Paz-Salinas, 2017). These characteristics give specificity to the notion of environmental justice in Latin America. There is, however, a key element that is often overlooked in the literature on the defence of life and territories: the religious sentiment that underlies a significant portion of the struggles, especially in territories of predominant indigenous and campesino identity. 3 Theoretical and methodological remarks Because scholarship in the field of environmental justice was built predominantly upon studies of western environmen- tal conflicts, it falls short of grasping the Latin American specificities detailed in the previous section. For that reason, critical scholars call for decolonizing environmental-justice studies (Álvarez and Coolsaet, 2018). According to these thinkers, the uncritical use of western conceptualizations to https://doi.org/10.5194/gh-75-403-2020 Geogr. Helv., 75, 403–414, 2020 https://modevite.wordpress.com/2019/08/21/comunicados/ https://sipaz.wordpress.com/2019/08/21/chiapas-megaperegrinacion-del-movimiento-en-defensa-de-la-vida-y-del-territorio-modevite-en-tuxtla-gutierrez/ 406 C. Ruiz-de-Oña Plaza: Between divine and social justice: emerging climate-justice narratives in Latin America Table 2. Characteristics of the Council of Maya Mam, Te Txe Chman, Guatemala, Department of San Marcos: Origin It was consolidated in 2009, as a sub-group of the regional organization the Council of the Mam People. Their principles of cohesion are based on the Mam ethnic identity. Context of emergence and religious adscription It was born in the context of the fight against the Marlin gold mine in San Miguel Ixtahuacán, and in other localities in the border Department of San Marcos. The fight was led by the Comunidades de Base (Base Communities) of liberation theology, led by Bishop Ramazzini. Structure and mode of operation It belongs to an extensive network of councils grouped by ethnicity and region, under the Major Council of Mayan Peoples, which operates in a decentralized manner at different levels (community, municipal, regional, and state levels). Along with its sister organizations, it has built an extensive and novel articulated political structure, with several branches that are under the umbrella body of the Council of Peoples of the West (CPO). Human–nature relationship It recovers and updates the ancestral leading figure of the indigenous authorities (considered to be the guardians of the common well-being) and other ancestral bodies of self-governance that according to the Council of Maya Mam have been in place since colonial times. Collective action Claims related to the right to self-determination or autonomy and its exercise over their territories. Promotion and practice of procedures for local consultation and collective decision. In 2005, in the Department of San Marcos, the Council of Maya Mam celebrated the first of 74 Consultas Comunitarias de Buena Fe (Community consultations of Good Faith) to register communities’ decisions on the presence of mining and other mega- projects. Justice claims Demand radical transformation of the Guatemalan state and the construction of a multinational state, not only in word, but also as de facto autonomy. These claims are expressed, for example, in the new constitution for the whole country, and in the council’s participation as a political party (Convergence) in two national elections. Political influence The Council of Peoples of the West has become one of the primary forms of political representation of indige- nous peoples. It has an agenda against the oppression of racist state politics and of questioning the forms of cap- ital accumulation implemented in the rural areas. It exhibits a strong capacity to act through legal and juridical procedures. It has developed a diverse and potent system of independent mass media, radio, web pages, jour- nals, and ceremonial celebration. However, it must confront a powerful counter-narrative disseminated through an equally potent mass media system, led by conservative and elite forces, that accuses human-rights defenders of being “terrorists”. Source: prepared by the author based on dispatches, news, and posts from https://www.prensacomunitaria.org/category/territorios/suroccidente/san-marcos/ (last access: 17 August 2020), https://cpo.org.gt/2019/?cat=43 (last access: 17 August 2020), https://cpo.org.gt/2019/?p=28 (last access: 17 August 2020), https://movimientom4.org/tag/consejo-del-pueblo-maya-cpo/ (last access: 17 August 2020), https://movimientom4.org/2016/10/declaracion-de-la-asamblea-nacional-del-consejo-del-pueblo-maya-cpo/ (last access: 17 August 2020) and http://consejodepueblosdeoccidente.blogspot.com/ (last access: 17 August 2020). analyse non-western environmental-justice conflicts can re- produce environmental injustices. In post-colonial settings, the environmental component has not been the decisive ar- gument for justice claims, despite its obvious relevance in structuring narratives of defence of life and territories. Previous studies, including recent environmental-justice scholarship conducted in Latin American scenarios (Car- ruthers, 2008; Hafner, 2018), have emphasized that environ- mental concerns cannot be detached from popular mobiliza- tions for social justice and equality (Carruthers, 2008:9, 12). Furthermore, recent scholars’ definitions of environmental justice have superseded earlier perspectives, which focused narrowly upon distributional aspects. The new definitions, which have become common in the literature, are more in- tegrative and inclusive and call for a more explicit conceptu- alization of how justice is understood (Pellow, 2017; Schlos- berg, 2009). To that end, Schlosberg argues for a broad, plu- ralist notion of justice that encompasses the human and the non-human world (Schlosberg, 2009:5). He also acknowl- edges the importance of having a multiplicity of justice no- tions that coexist at the individual and collective levels and which include not only distributional issues but also recogni- tion, participation, and functioning (Schlosberg, 2009:4). Hafner (2018) proposes an innovative framework, based on revealing local structures and elements of thought style, for analysing environmental justice in temporal and spatial contexts (Hafner, 2018:3). The proposed framework allows for the identification of local concerns and claims. Such an approach may enable researchers to understand which grounds local people invoke (or not) in their claims of justice. It can also reveal the importance of pre-conflict stages and why open conflict does or does not result (Hafner, 2018:2). Hafner’s emphasis on the epistemology of cognition, par- ticularly the visceral cognitive elements thereof, opens a new horizon of analysis: one that makes room for the in- terconnectedness of the rational and the emotional (Hafner, 2018:232). Hafner’s work is only one example of recent con- ceptual developments in environmental-justice theory that Geogr. Helv., 75, 403–414, 2020 https://doi.org/10.5194/gh-75-403-2020 https://www.prensacomunitaria.org/category/territorios/suroccidente/san-marcos/ https://cpo.org.gt/2019/?cat=43 https://cpo.org.gt/2019/?p=28 https://movimientom4.org/tag/consejo-del-pueblo-maya-cpo/ https://movimientom4.org/2016/10/declaracion-de-la-asamblea-nacional-del-consejo-del-pueblo-maya-cpo/ http://consejodepueblosdeoccidente.blogspot.com/ C. Ruiz-de-Oña Plaza: Between divine and social justice: emerging climate-justice narratives in Latin America 407 Figure 1. Location of the Maya Mam cross-border area in the southern section of the border of Chiapas and Guatemala. The map details the composition of the religious diversity of the municipalities on the Mexican side (there are no disaggregated data for the municipalities of San Marcos, Guatemala). Prepared by Yair Merlin. Source: INEGI, 2010. National Population and Housing Census 2010. National Institute of Statistics and Geography. Aguascalientes, Mexico. Consulted in July 2020. Available at https://www.inegi.org.mx/temas/religion/ (last access: 15 July 2020). would be particularly relevant when representing the com- plex Latin American socio-environmental struggles as a ma- joritarian expression of resistance. However, environmental- justice theory still needs to incorporate the religious dimen- sion that animates most of these struggles. In the work reported in the present article, I follow a nar- rative approach to analyse qualitative data under an interpre- tative paradigm. By using the term narrative, I follow Riess- man (2008) in meaning the elaboration of stories that func- tion as devices through which the actors position themselves and attribute specific ideas of “responsibility”, “guilt”, “vic- timization”, “urgency”, “disaster”, “the rational”, or “valid behaviours” in statements located temporarily and spatially. These statements can be oral, written, or graphic about a vital experience or conjunctural event (Arnold, 2018). During the personal or collective process of constructing the narrative, identity elements of a historical nature come into play (Tam- boukou, 2013) to promote mobilization for social change, or to invite audiences to enter the perspective of the story- teller (Elliott, 2005). Analytically, I follow Riessman in “[ex- amining] primarily what content a narrative communicates, rather than how a narrative is constructed [. . .] by examin- ing how stories of resistance generate collective action in so- cial movements” (Riessman, 2008:73). The narrative analy- sis that I present was based upon secondary sources obtained from dispatches, notices, political manifests, and alternative- press news that served communicative and political purposes. I also interviewed the Guatemala coordinator of the Global Catholic Climate Movement. The narrative threads identified in those documents and interviews allowed me to access the socio-environmental movements’ notions of environmental justice and to identify emergent climate-justice claims. Also included are observations about the transborder region of the Tacaná volcano during the municipal and presidential elec- toral campaign in the Guatemala municipality of Sibinal, in the Department of San Marcos. 4 Climate justice and the religion factor in socio-environmental struggles As in the case of environmental-justice conceptions, dom- inant conceptualizations of climate justice do not contem- https://doi.org/10.5194/gh-75-403-2020 Geogr. Helv., 75, 403–414, 2020 https://www.inegi.org.mx/temas/religion/ 408 C. Ruiz-de-Oña Plaza: Between divine and social justice: emerging climate-justice narratives in Latin America plate the effect of religious feelings in calls for climate jus- tice. Instead, research has employed a philosophical and eth- ical perspective that focuses upon the just distribution of burdens and entitlements and upon the differentiation of re- sponsibilities in the realm of adaptation and mitigation (see Harris, 2019). In the international political arena, the United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change (UN- FCCC) enunciated the principle of “shared but differentiated responsibilities”. That principle established the need to cre- ate specific funds to finance the adaptation efforts of devel- oping countries (Honty, 2011). Historical emissions of devel- oped countries have been at the centre of a polemic debate between developed and developing countries. Honty rightly points to the incontrovertible fact that climate change will take place in an unequal world. Present inequalities will, on the whole, grow as the impacts of climate change increase (Honty, 2011:19). In Latin America, calls for justice as recognition of his- torical responsibility, and not only as a fair distribution of burdens and costs, can be identified in arguments made by countries such as Bolivia. On this matter, Forsyth (2014) points out the need to reassess justice frameworks that are based upon distribution approaches. That reassessment would allow for a wider range of solutions. He also advocates Sen’s approach to justice as a means of moving beyond di- chotomies based upon distributional and procedural justice, and thereby initiating a more open and inclusive debate about risks and solutions. In general, the limited achievements of international cli- mate negotiations have left researchers with a sense of failure and mistrust. As a result, researchers now pay more attention to other sources of motivation for action. Among these, re- ligion seems to be gaining unusual strength in the realm of climate justice. 4.1 The religious and climatic elements in MODEVITE and the Council of Maya Mam narratives of struggle In liberation theology, and specifically in the encyclical Laudato si’, climate justice is considered an ethical imper- ative. The encyclical points directly to the need to base inter- national mitigation policies upon principles of climate justice (Kerber, 2010). It reacts against the mercantilist and instru- mental rationality of the present policies, from which the hu- man and ethical dimension is absent. Along somewhat sim- ilar lines, recent developments in Latin American liberation theology (see Boff, 2011) incorporate a renewed theology of creation, along with the Latin American ecofeminist perspec- tive and the development of an indigenous theology (Kerber, 2010). Laudato si’ integrates these developments to build a critique that attacks the pillars of the current economic system. The encyclical’s goal of radically transforming the paradigm of modern civilization entails a reconstruction of the human–nature link. The subtitle of the encyclical (“On Care for Our Common Home”) synthesizes the integration and belonging of the human in nature. The following in- sights about the encyclical’s bases and goals are offered by Efraín Bámaka, who is a certified animador (local promoter) of Laudato si’ and coordinator of the Guatemala chapter of the Catholic Climate Movement, as well as a researcher at the Universidad de San Carlos de Guatemala: (. . .) in paragraph 51 it is mentioned that “inequity does not only affect individuals but entire coun- tries” there it speaks and forces us to think about ethics of international relations, because there is a real ecological debt, and here what I want to mention (. . .) is particularly between the north and the south, related to trade imbalances, with con- sequences in the ecological field as well as the disproportionate use of natural resources histori- cally carried out by some countries. And then it comes to talk about exports, that is, it is a document that from a socio-political analysis, talks about and even goes beyond climate justice, which it does mention: we need a cultural revolution (EBL, Hue- huetenango, 30 June 2020). But how do social movements incorporate these tenets into the daily struggle for environmental and climate jus- tice in unique territories? In the borderlands of Chiapas and Guatemala, two key socio-environmental movements have been leading the fight for environmental justice in the con- text of confrontations with international mining exploitation. The first movement is the Council of Maya Mam Te Txe Chman, an ancestral governing body of the Maya Mam peo- ple of the San Marcos department, Guatemala (see Table 2). The second is the Movement for the Defence of Life and Territory (MODEVITE), a coalition of catholic indigenous organizations with a presence in some territories of Chiapas. Both movements draw upon liberation theology but incor- porate climate justice in a differentiated manner and with variable intensity throughout the borderlands. Those lands, which are part of the ancestral territories of the Mam Mayan ethnic group, extend over a portion of the cross-border area between Chiapas and Guatemala. The Tacaná volcano area, which straddles the border, is significant because of the con- trasting degrees of environmental conflict and struggle expe- rienced on the two sides. The shared colonial past of this region includes marginal- ization, exclusion, violence, and the imposition of the Catholic religion. Even today, half of the region’s inhabitants are professing Catholics. (See Fig. 1; no disaggregated data are available for Guatemala.) However, religious diversity is now evident in this region, as well as throughout Guatemala and Chiapas (which is Mexico’s most religiously diverse state). Protestant denominations of quite varied creeds have a significant presence, with evangelical and neo-Pentecostal religions predominating. The church of liberation theology is a prominent feature of the religious profile throughout this transboundary region. Geogr. Helv., 75, 403–414, 2020 https://doi.org/10.5194/gh-75-403-2020 C. Ruiz-de-Oña Plaza: Between divine and social justice: emerging climate-justice narratives in Latin America 409 Both the Council of Maya Mam and MODEVITE (see Ta- bles 1 and 2 for descriptions) are community-oriented move- ments that use religion as a means of community develop- ment “to improve the well-being of a community, often in the face of a repressive government” (Kirmani, 2008:29). Kirmani remarks that although religious feelings are an important factor in mobilizing collective action (Kirmani, 2008:33), the acts of resistance and improvement of well- being are varied and are not restricted to the celebration of the faiths. A particularly relevant example is the improve- ment of agricultural systems from an agroecological perspec- tive. Nevertheless, for MODEVITE as well as the Council of Maya Mam every action, resistance, and confrontation rests upon a religious sentiment. MODEVITE provided a clear ex- ample of this through the communiqué that it read to the pub- lic during MODEVITE’s pilgrimage of 20 August 2019. In that communiqué, the sacred dimension of both the protest and its content is manifest. The communiqué alludes to the belonging of the Believing People to mother earth as the source of the people’s primary nourishment. The commu- niqué also invokes a timeless dimension that lives in the memory of the ancestors. The circular temporality expressed here is one of life and death in the continuous rebirth of na- ture. In contrast, the survival of capitalist production is con- ditioned by the constant growth conceived from a linear tem- porality. As the communiqué explained, we have gone out again to walk and to speak our word; we are of the original peoples with a face and a heart of our own, born of Mother Earth and corn, with a spiritual relationship woven into life and ter- ritory. In this way we remember the memory of our grandmothers and grandfathers: we are earth, we are fire, we are air, we are defenders and caretakers of Mother Earth (https://modevite.wordpress.com/ 2019/08/21/comunicados/, last access: 29 Decem- ber 2019). The religious adherence of the Mexican movement MOD- EVITE is exclusively to the Catholic faith based on liber- ation theology. In Guatemala, the Council of Maya Mam, too, emerged from the church of liberation theology. How- ever, the council now gives greater weight to the Mam ethnic identity than to religious affiliation. As a result, the coun- cil has greater religious diversity than MODEVITE. Some council members have no defined religion. Nevertheless, the council’s identification with the church of liberation theology remains strong, and some of the council’s most emblematic leaders are also community leaders in the ecclesial base com- munities (EBL, coordinator of the Guatemala Chapter of the Catholic Climate Movement and animator Laudato si’, Hue- huetenango, Guatemala, 30 June 2020). Ancient Maya Mam beliefs are an additional religious element in the council; the recovery and re-creation of those beliefs plays a vital role in the upper ranks of the council’s intellectuals (Consejo del Pueblo Maya, 2019:6–7). In both MODEVITE and the Maya Mam council, women play a vital and decisive role as drivers of collective ac- tion. Strong organizational ties based on ethnic and reli- gious adscription give way to an innovative mechanism of self-governance and self-representation in both movements. Each has a communal structure of authorities: “Consultas de Buena Fe” in the case of the council and the constitution of “plurinational community governmental bodies” in MODE- VITE (see Tables 1 and 2). The political strength of these structures has shown itself in socio-environmental struggles against mega-projects. 4.2 Climate-justice narratives emerging in MODEVITE and the Council of Maya Mam The two movements differ in the degrees to which they refer to the climate justice that was proclaimed in the encyclical Laudato si’. MODEVITE makes no specific mention of cli- mate change in the pronouncements and communiqués that it has issued in the context of its struggle. In contrast, the Council of Maya Mam, in association with its sister organi- zations, is gradually inserting allusions to climate change in its manifests and public statements. (See for example Prensa Comunitaria Km. 169.) The council’s sister organizations in- clude councils of various ethnic identities, as well as a range of social organizations fighting for the defence of life and ter- ritory. A prominent example is the peasant workers’ move- ment of San Marcos. References to climate change appear in the council’s communiqués that address the violent real- ity that confronts its members. The communiqués denounce extractive enterprises; condemn the mining companies’ ex- pulsions, land-grabbing, and environmental damage; demand the release of political prisoners; and seek justice for victims of murders and human-rights violations. The council also referred to climate change, albeit indi- rectly, when it joined several indigenous organizations in supporting the Food Sovereignty Network’s communiqué en- titled “Climate Change and Mega-crops also threaten our food sovereignty and the human right to food” (issued 21 September 2015). The communiqué’s narrative reveals how climate change, in the context of the struggle of socio- environmental movements in Guatemala, is linked to the ex- tractive industry and its impacts on social and environmen- tal issues. The narrative also relates the intensity of systemic violence in the border territories of San Marcos. Going far beyond the carbon accounting that is so prominent in inter- national politics, the communiqué alludes to the effects of climate change upon human rights and vital needs like food sovereignty. In short, the tone of the narrative that the com- muniqué constructs around the impacts of climate change is markedly condemnatory – a striking contrast to the logic by which international climate-mitigation policies operate. Moreover, the condemnation is accompanied by a demand for social justice, for respecting human rights, and for the https://doi.org/10.5194/gh-75-403-2020 Geogr. Helv., 75, 403–414, 2020 https://modevite.wordpress.com/2019/08/21/comunicados/ https://modevite.wordpress.com/2019/08/21/comunicados/ 410 C. Ruiz-de-Oña Plaza: Between divine and social justice: emerging climate-justice narratives in Latin America protection of nature (which is always referred to as mother earth). The Council of Maya Mam works in partnership with organizations such as the nongovernmental organization (NGO) “Commission for Peace and Ecology” (in Spanish, the COPAE). COPAE is dedicated to conducting research on local realities, to training, and to dissemination of knowledge about sustainability, justice, environment, and ecology. CO- PAE’s outreach is a source of information for communiqués and public proclamations. Significantly, for our purposes, COPAE is also a source of information for the teachings car- ried out in ecclesial communities to which many grassroots members of the Council of Maya Mam belong. From the lo- cal parishes in alliance with COPAE, a path emerges for lo- cal understandings of the impacts of climate change and of how the configuration of those impacts is a question of jus- tice in terms of a north–south debt. These understandings are always balanced with the local communities’ most pressing matters: the idea was that we have elements for the strug- gle that emerged from the investigation, so per- haps that’s why you begin to notice certain words, certain discourses that are more formed or that epistemically go beyond mere experience and that even have in their language some epistemic no- tion, because they already speak to you about these questions as well (EBL, Huehuetenango, 30 June 2020). The channelling of Laudato si’ climate-justice proposals to the ecclesial grassroots communities is progressing gradu- ally, and according to the increasingly felt effects of climate change: (. . .) as a result of this question of the encyclical, the discourse on climate justice is present, but I feel that it is still a great absence, why? Look when you go to the border to these territories of San Marcos, because the people have been affected, the people talk to you about climate justice, even generational justice, but if you come to the central plateau, cli- mate change and the environment does not mean anything to the people, because they feel that it does not affect them; instead, the people of San Marcos are affected because the mine was there, where the gold was taken from their land, where the water was stolen from their land, so, those peo- ple have already taken a stand on that discourse (EBL, Huehuetenango, 30 June 2020). 4.3 Two countries, one ethnic origin: the ancestral territory of the Maya Mam between Chiapas (Mexico) and San Marcos (Guatemala) The region of study, which was once an ecological and cul- tural unity, is now divided by the international border that slices through the very peak of the Tacaná volcano. Differ- ent fates awaited the Maya Mam people who found them- selves living on opposite sides of this line, which was drawn through their ancestral highland territory (Toledo Pineda and Coraza de los Santos, 2019). The region provides contrast- ing scenarios concerning the presence and intensity of socio- environmental struggles. The contrasts reveal how specific types of state regimes shape socio-environmental struggles in a particularized manner. During the late 19th century, Mam people on both sides of the border were forced to work as peons in the system of fincas – coffee plantations owned by European and North American nationals. Later, the Mexican revolution and ensu- ing agrarian reform enabled descendants of Maya Mam pe- ons in Mexico to hold lands communally, as ejidos. Land for that purpose was granted in the 1930s, during the presidency of Lázaro Cárdenas (Hernández Castillo, 2012). This region was privileged during Mexico’s agrarian reform: most of the privately owned coffee lands were transferred to groups of landless peasants, who were primarily ethnic Mam people of Guatemalan nationality. In the Mexican part of the region of study, the long shadow of the revolution – agrarian reform, plus a state where paternalism still thrives – has produced state–campesino relationships quite different than in neigh- bouring Guatemala. Although the defence of life and territories motto is pro- claimed widely in communities on both sides of the border, the communities’ experiences with extractive industries in this region are quite different across the border. San Mar- cos in Guatemala is an emblematic territory in the strug- gle against mining companies – and especially against the Marlin gold mine. The struggle is led by prominent mem- bers of the liberation theology church, such as Bishop Ra- mazzini. In contrast, the presence of mining companies has not been so intense in the Mexican part of the Tacaná. Nev- ertheless, small conflicts have occurred, especially within the Tacaná Biosphere Reserve, where various interests have prospected for ore deposits and attempted to install a micro- hydroelectric plant. These conflicts caused an explosion of support for MODEVITE in 2015–2016 (field observations and informal conversations with communal authorities of the Chespal community in Tacaná, September 2016, April 2019). More generally, communities on the Mexican side work hand in hand with the ecclesial base communities and adhere to the justice claims of MODEVITE to fight against mega- infrastructure and energy projects. On the Guatemala side of the Tacaná volcano region, in the Department of San Marcos, the Council of Maya Mam has a strong presence throughout several municipalities. Socio- environmental struggles occur within an exacerbated context of repression and lack of democratic guarantees (Consejo del Pueblo Maya, 2014, 2019; Rivera, 2016). The oligarchi- cal state has never acceded to a redistribution of power and wealth, nor did it vanish after the 36-year civil war. Even now, in post-conflict times, the Guatemalan state remains Geogr. Helv., 75, 403–414, 2020 https://doi.org/10.5194/gh-75-403-2020 C. Ruiz-de-Oña Plaza: Between divine and social justice: emerging climate-justice narratives in Latin America 411 Figure 2. MODEVITE placard on the southern border of Chia- pas, rejecting mining in the area: “No to mining, yes to life. We want beans and corn. Get the miners out of the country”. Ecclesial communities of the base. Municipality of Chicomuselo, border with Guatemala, 30 July 2017. Photograph taken by the author. a racialized discriminatory regime, as is made evident by the highly unequal distribution of land (Granovsky-Larsen, 2019). In these struggles, representatives of the church of the theology of liberation were vital to shaping the battle and or- ganizing the people via grassroots communities. As a result, the communities’ relations with the state have configured a different political arena for socio-environmental activism. A critical feature of the political context is the co-opting of movements by a network of historical and newly emerging economic elites of the state apparatus. In addition, illegal violence is used against human-rights defenders, independent judges, and anybody opposing the elites’ power (Aguilar-Støen and Bull, 2016). Food secu- rity and sovereignty are seriously jeopardized by extreme poverty, the highly uneven distribution of land, and the on- going 4-year drought in key agricultural areas of the country (Orgaz, 2019). In this context, the Council of Maya Mam struggles not only for the defence of water, land, and terri- tories, but also to build a new state: one that is “inclusive of all of the Guatemalan peoples, independently of ethnicity, re- ligion or political ideology, a state that acknowledges unity in the diversity” (25 March 2019, Meeting of the Conver- gence Party, the new political party emerging from the Con- sejo Mayor Mam and the Consejo de Pueblos de Occidente, Sibinal, Department of San Marcos). Returning to the Mexican side of the region, we see an intertwining of religious and patriotic sentiments in MOD- EVITE’s protest marches, which MODEVITE refers to as “pilgrimages” (a religious term). Patriotic symbols of Mex- ican iconography like the national flag fly over the marches alongside representations of the Virgin of Guadalupe. Other religious symbols appear as well, and some of the priests who participate wear indigenous motifs on their clothes. MODE- VITE questions the Mexican state but still considers it to be a reference point and a valid interlocutor. Even on MODE- VITE’s website, praise for Jesus is combined with that for Emiliano Zapata, an iconic figure of the Mexican revolution and the neo-Zapatism: “Viva Jesús! Viva Zapata!”. In stark contrast, the Council of Maya Mam sees nothing to exalt in Guatemala’s national past. The council identifies the Guatemalan state clearly as the critical source of oppres- sion against the Mam people and the main party responsible for the devastation of their territory. Thus, the transformation of the Guatemalan state in its historical and current confor- mation is the ultimate objective of the council’s struggle: there is a document called the Political Constitu- tion of the Mam People, and even I worked on that constitution. (. . .) we received a lot of criticism be- cause how is someone going to make a constitu- tion? Because there is only one constitution, that of the country. But no, they come and work and say this is our constitution. It’s a document from Octo- ber 2018. In the first chapter, first section, it says, “We stand at the side of all the struggles that seek a radical reorganization of the State of Guatemala” (. . .); when they refer to the State of Guatemala it is in small letters, and from there it is an interest- ing question, both in writing and in speech. In that sense, the Mam people see the State as their op- pressor (EBL, Huehuetenango, 30 June 2020). 5 Discussion and conclusions In local territories crisscrossed and lacerated by neo- extractivism, the religious feeling emanating from liberation theology provides a sense of strength, union, and transcen- dence that counterbalances the power wielded by the state in coalition with mining and agro-industrial empires. This is especially true for San Marcos, Guatemala, where the state still refuses to recognize the most basic rights of the majority of its population. Instead, the state’s policies of marginaliz- ing and slowly exterminating ethnic identities continue un- interrupted. Therefore, as indicated by the drafting of the above-mentioned political constitution of the Mam people, the Council of Maya Mam aspires to a fundamental transfor- mation of the country. In the new Guatemala, the Mam would have rights as a nation within the framework of a plurina- tional state governed by the rule of law. Meanwhile, the church of the poor of liberation theology and the narrative of “The Care of the Common House” are playing a leading role in defining a concept of climate jus- tice that matches the interests of local populations. Libera- tion theology provides a sense of justice anchored not only in the here and now, but also in the recognition of a circu- lar temporality that binds together past, present, and future generations. These aspects of liberation theology are evident https://doi.org/10.5194/gh-75-403-2020 Geogr. Helv., 75, 403–414, 2020 412 C. Ruiz-de-Oña Plaza: Between divine and social justice: emerging climate-justice narratives in Latin America in efforts by the church of the poor of liberation theology to build and disseminate claims to social, environmental, and climate justice. The church incorporates Indian theology and a blend of ancestral knowledge and scientific research, while the church’s reticular organization reaches out to remote vil- lages and municipal capitals through parishes and their grass- roots groups. Recent international research on environmental justice has evolved towards understanding the integration of sensory, emotional, and instrumental motivations. However, the expe- rience of socio-environmental struggles in Latin America re- veals the need to pay attention to the religious dimension that is present in notions of environmental and climate justice. In the context of those struggles, the idea of environmental and climate justice goes beyond the dimensions of participation, distribution, functioning, and recognition: it rests on a sense of historical grievance and is supported by intense religious feeling. The intensities of these historical and religious sentiments are different on the two sides of the cross-border region of study because of divergent relations – past and present – with the respective figures of the state. The notion of climate justice has not been fully developed within the local bases of MODEVITE or in the Council of Maya Mam. However, that notion is increasingly incorporated in the council’s dec- larations, communiqués, news, and proclamations of strug- gle. From these communiqués, a notion of multi-scale cli- mate crisis emerges. On the one hand, the crisis is under- stood on a global scale as affecting the entire human broth- erhood as part of the planet, along with all our fellow in- habitants of the “common house”. At the same time, the crisis is local, with concrete and differential expressions in the territories affected by neo-extractivism and the impacts of climate change. This idea of climate justice cannot be conceived in isolation from the demands for social justice, which invoke the long history of grievances and violations of human rights against indigenous communities. Hence, the notions of environmental and climate justice cannot be un- derstood in a standardized way: they emerge from the ex- perience of struggle in territories crossed by a complex set of historical and present causes. A fundamental dimension in new environmental-justice reformulations is the realiza- tion that Latin American socio-environmental struggles are, in many cases, of an ontological nature (Blaser, 2009). That is, they are a fight both for life itself and to give life a new and deeper definition. These new formulations can serve very different contexts, in late modern societies as well as in loca- tions with a colonial past. How might definitions of environmental justice incorpo- rate the ontological nature of environmental struggles along with the intertwined structural and subjective dimensions? The environmental-justice field must explicitly consider the socially constructed nature of “environment” and “justice”. The meanings of these notions differ among cultures and political contexts because those meanings are mediated for the direct emotional, symbolic, and social experience and attachment to the territories from which they emerge (Nar- chi, 2015). Thus, the meaning of environment cannot be re- stricted to the narrow concept of a biophysical entity de- tached from the social sphere. Accordingly, a variety of ra- tionalities give rise to notions of justice and nature that are distinct, in different degrees, from westernized perspectives (Álvarez and Coolsaet 2018). The Laudato si’ aligns well with the suggested broaden- ings of perspectives and meanings: it advocates for integrat- ing the reformulation of the current techno-science of cli- mate policies with cordial, emotional, and visceral rationality (Boff, 2019:6). Thus, the encyclical is also in tune with Mbe- mbe’s critique and with Hafner’s proposal about the inclusion of the sensorial in the conceptualizations of environmental justice. The importance of such proposals is made clear by the concrete experiences (e.g. those presented here) of social movements that have strong components of indigenous and religious identity. Within the narratives of these movements, elements of modern and traditional combinations of rational- ities can configure environmental- and climate-justice claims that depart from idealized pictures of the noble savage. A further example of combining modern and traditional rationalities is seen in the indigenous movements’ struggles for the right to constitute their own authorities (rather than have them imposed by the state). That right, which plays a vital role in the Latin American context, is based on ances- tral imaginaries. However, the movements’ purpose in strug- gling for that right is to be able to redefine the desired type of modernity in their own terms. Thus, the movements are spaces for decision and collective action that constitute true references for the enunciation of place-based notions of en- vironmental and climate justice. Social and environmental climatic justice is strongly influenced here by the reflective and transforming practice of liberation theology (thinking– judging–acting). Within that practice, social movements find a source of legitimacy: justice with a transcendental dimen- sion, instead of one that is disjointed from social and envi- ronmental justice in the here and now. The multiplicity that is present in that dimension needs to be part of environmental- justice definitions. Being aware of that range of different meanings opens the possibility of a real dialogue. On the con- trary, taken-for-granted conversations conducted under the belief or supposition of a common understanding of uncriti- cally assumed concepts will sap the power and creativity that we need for a battle in which we, as humanity, have no way out. Data availability. The data from this research are largely of an ethnographic nature and are not publicly available for the following reasons: the field observations, informal conversations, and ethno- graphic records were entered into a largely undigitized field diary; they are part of broader ongoing research that addresses other is- sues, particularly related to coffee, and were recorded following Geogr. Helv., 75, 403–414, 2020 https://doi.org/10.5194/gh-75-403-2020 C. Ruiz-de-Oña Plaza: Between divine and social justice: emerging climate-justice narratives in Latin America 413 ethical considerations of privacy and anonymity when requested; and the transcripts of interviews conducted and their recordings were made with the consent of the individuals interviewed to main- tain their privacy and in some cases may contain sensitive informa- tion that the interviewee requested not to be disclosed. For inter- views with the name of the interviewee visible, the transcript may be shared as long as permission is sought from both the intervie- wee and the researcher. Secondary data from websites and statistical censuses are of a public nature and accessible to anyone. Supplement. The supplement related to this article is available online at: https://doi.org/10.5194/gh-75-403-2020-supplement. Competing interests. The author declares that there is no con- flict of interest. Acknowledgements. My deepest thanks to the people of Sibi- nal, San Marcos, and Unión Juárez for sharing their lives and giv- ing us shelter and for their friendship. Special thanks to Efraín Bá- maca López, for sharing his knowledge, and to Yair Merlín Uribe for the realization of the religious distribution map and for the reli- gious tabulations. I am also grateful for the comments made by the three anonymous reviewers. Review statement. This paper was edited by Jonas Hein and re- viewed by three anonymous referees. References Aguilar-Støen, M. and Bull, B.: Protestas contra minería en Guatemala, Anuario de Estudios Centroamericanos, 42, 15–44, 2016. Alimonda, H. (Ed.): La naturaleza colonizada: ecología política y minería en América Latina, 1. ed., Ediciones CICCUS: CLACSO, Buenos Aires, 2011. Álvarez, L. and Coolsaet, B.: Decolonising Environ- mental Justice Studies: A Latin American Per- spective, Capitalism Nature Socialism, 31, 50–69, https://doi.org/10.1080/10455752.2018.1558272, 2018. Arnold, A.: Climate Change and Storytelling: Narratives and Cul- tural Meaning in Environmental Communication, Springer Na- ture, Switzerland, 2018. Bastos, S. and de León, Q.: Dinámicas de despojo y resistencia en Guatemala. Comunidades, Estado y empresas, Colibrí Zurdo, Serviprensa, Guatemala, C.A., 2014. Beling, A. E. and Vanhulst, J.: Desarrollo non sancto: la religión como actor emergente en el debate global sobre el futuro del planeta, 400 Siglo XXI Editores, Ciudad de México, Mexico, 2019. Bergmann, S.: Climate Change Changes Religion: Space, Spirit, Ritual, Technology – through a Theological Lens, Stu- dia Theologica, Nordic Journal of Theology, 63, 98–118, https://doi.org/10.1080/00393380903345057, 2009. Blaser, M.: Political ontology: Cultural Studies without “cultures”?, Cult. Stud., 23, 873896, https://doi.org/10.1080/09502380903208023, 2009. Boff, L.: Lo esencial del Evangelio, lo nuevo de la ecoteología: qué aporta el cristianismo a la humanidad en esta fase planetaria, Nueva Utopía, Madrid, Spain, 2011. Boff, L.: Prólogo, in Desarrollo Non Sancto. La religión como actor emergente en el debate global sobre el futuro del planeta, edited by: Beiling, A. E. and Vanhulst, J., Siglo XXI Editores, Ciudad de México, Mexico, 7–12, 2019. Botero, D. I. R. and Galeano, C. A. P.: Territories in Dis- pute: Tensions between “Extractivism”, Ethnic Rights, Local Governments and the 410 Environment in Bolivia, Colombia, Ecuador and Peru, in Alternative Pathways to Sustainable De- velopment: Lessons from Latin America, edited by: Carbon- nier, G., Campodónico, H., and Tezanos Vázquez, S., 269–290, Brill | Nijhoff, Leiden, the Netherlands, Boston, Massachusetts, USA, https://doi.org/10.1163/9789004351677_013, 2017. de la Cadena, M.: Indigenous Cosmopolitics in the An- des: cosmopolitics in the Andes: Conceptual Reflec- tions beyond “Politics”, Cult. Anthropol., 25, 334–370, https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1548-1360.2010.01061.x, 2010. Carruthers, D. V.: Popular environmentalism and social justice in Latin America., in Environmental justice in Latin America: prob- lems, promise, and practice, edited by: Carruthers, D. V., MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, USA, 2008. Consejo del Pueblo Maya: Un nuevo estado para Guatemala., Proyecto Política, CPO, Guatemala, available at: https://drive.google.com/file/d/ 0B31fnGLtBsbMLWR1ZkdrX3A0MWc/view?fbclid= IwAR1r3rebSoTp28Yn-5p1WAgS8o1n97Wzbrk0cOMmZr_ _MEpMmmhvbPbyuPU (last access: 2 April 2019), 2014. Consejo del Pueblo Maya: Articulación política del Pueblo Maya., CPO, Guatemala, available at: https://cpo.org.gt/2019/ conocenos/, last access: 12 April 2019. Elliott, J.: Using Narrative in Social Research: Qualitative and Quantitative Approaches, SAGE Publications Ltd., London, UK, 2005. Escobar, A.: Sentipensar-con-la-tierra. Nuevas lecturas sobre de- sarrollo, territorio y diferencia, Ediciones UNAULA, Medellín, Colombia, 184 pp., 2014. Forsyth, T.: Climate justice is not just ice, Geoforum, 54, 230–232, https://doi.org/10.1016/j.geoforum.2012.12.008, 2014. Gerten, D. and Bergmann, S. (Eds.): Religion in Environmental and Climate Change: Suffering, Values, Lifestyles, Continuum Inter- national Publishing Group, London, UK, New York, NY, USA, 2011. Gottlieb, R. S. (Ed.): The Oxford Handbook of Religion and Ecol- ogy, Oxford University Press, Oxford, USA, 2010. Granovsky-Larsen, S.: Dealing with Peace. The Guatemalan Campesino Movement and Post-Conflict Neoliberal State, Uni- versity of Toronto Press, Toronto Buffalo, London, Canada, 2019. Grosfoguel, R.: La descolonización del conocimiento: diálogo crítico entre la visión descolonial de Frantz Fanon y la so- ciología descolonial de Boaventura de Sousa Santos, Formas- Otras: Saber, nombrar, narrar, hacer, CIDOB, Barcelona, Spain, 97–108, 2011. https://doi.org/10.5194/gh-75-403-2020 Geogr. Helv., 75, 403–414, 2020 https://doi.org/10.5194/gh-75-403-2020-supplement https://doi.org/10.1080/10455752.2018.1558272 https://doi.org/10.1080/00393380903345057 https://doi.org/10.1080/09502380903208023 https://doi.org/10.1163/9789004351677_013 https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1548-1360.2010.01061.x https://drive.google.com/file/d/0B31fnGLtBsbMLWR1ZkdrX3A0MWc/view?fbclid=IwAR1r3rebSoTp28Yn-5p1WAgS8o1n97Wzbrk0cOMmZr__MEpMmmhvbPbyuPU https://drive.google.com/file/d/0B31fnGLtBsbMLWR1ZkdrX3A0MWc/view?fbclid=IwAR1r3rebSoTp28Yn-5p1WAgS8o1n97Wzbrk0cOMmZr__MEpMmmhvbPbyuPU https://drive.google.com/file/d/0B31fnGLtBsbMLWR1ZkdrX3A0MWc/view?fbclid=IwAR1r3rebSoTp28Yn-5p1WAgS8o1n97Wzbrk0cOMmZr__MEpMmmhvbPbyuPU https://drive.google.com/file/d/0B31fnGLtBsbMLWR1ZkdrX3A0MWc/view?fbclid=IwAR1r3rebSoTp28Yn-5p1WAgS8o1n97Wzbrk0cOMmZr__MEpMmmhvbPbyuPU https://cpo.org.gt/2019/conocenos/ https://cpo.org.gt/2019/conocenos/ https://doi.org/10.1016/j.geoforum.2012.12.008 414 C. Ruiz-de-Oña Plaza: Between divine and social justice: emerging climate-justice narratives in Latin America Hafner, R.: Environmental Justice and Soy Agribusiness, in: Earth- scan food and agriculture, 1st ed., Routledge, Taylor & Fran- cis Group, London, New York, NY, INBN 978-0-8153-8535-6, 2018. Haluza-DeLay, R.: Religion and Climate Change: Varieties in Viewpoints and Practices, WIRES Clim. Change, 5, 261–279, https://doi.org/10.1002/wcc.268, 2014. Harris, P. G. (Ed.): A research agenda for climate justice, Edward Elgar Publishing, Northampton, UK, 2019. Hernández Castillo, R. A.: Sur profundo: identidades indígenas en la frontera Chiapas-Guatemala, Centro de Investigaciones y Es- tudios Superiores en Antropologia Social, México, 2012. Honty, G.: Cambio Climático: negociaciones y consecuencias para América Latina, Coscoroba/CLAES, Uruguay, 2011. Jenkins, W.: Feasts of the Anthropocene: Beyond Climate Change as Special Object in the Study of Religion, South Atlantic Quar- terly, 116, 69–81, https://doi.org/10.1215/00382876-3749326, 2017. Kerber, G.: Climate change and Southern theologies. A Latin American insight. (As alterações climáticas e as teologias do sul. Uma visão da América Latina, HORIZONTE) – Re- vista de Estudos de Teologia e Ciências da Religião, 45–55, https://doi.org/10.5752/P.2175-5841.2010v8n17p45, 2010. Kirmani, N.: The Relationships between Social Movements and Re- ligion in Processes of Social Change: A Preliminary Literature Review, Religions and Development Research Program, Inter- national Development Department, University of Birmingham, Department for International Development (DFID), UK, 2008. Leff, E.: La apuesta por la vida: imaginación sociológica e imagi- narios sociales en los territorios ambientales del sur, Siglo XXI Editores, México DF, Mexico, 2014. Lorentzen, L. A. and Salvador, L.-A.: Religion and Environmental Struggles in Latin America, in: The Oxford Handbook of Reli- gion and Ecology, edited by: Gottlieb, R. S., 510–534, Oxford University Press, Oxford, USA, 2006. Mbembe, A.: Necropolitics, Public Culture, 15, 11–40, 2003. Mignolo, W. D. and Escobar, A. (Eds.): Globalization and the Decolonial Option, 1st ed., Routledge, New York, NY, USA, Canada, 2013. Narchi, N. E.: Environmental Violence in Mexico: A Con- ceptual Introduction, Lat. Am. Perspect., 42, 5–18, https://doi.org/10.1177/0094582X15579909, 2015. Navarro, M. L.: Subjetividades políticas contra el despojo capital- ista de bienes naturales en México, Acta Sociol., 62, 135–153, https://doi.org/10.1016/S0186-6028(13)71002-8, 2013. Orgaz, C. J.: ¿Qué es el Corredor Seco y por qué está ligado a la po- breza extrema en casi toda Centroamérica?, available at: https: //www.bbc.com/mundo/noticias-america-latina-48186820 (last access: 16 May 2019), 15 May 2019. Paz-Salinas, M. F.: Luchas en defensa del territorio. Reflexiones desde los conflictos socio-ambientales en México, Acta Sociol., 73, 197–219, https://doi.org/10.1016/j.acso.2017.08.007, 2017. Pellow, D. N.: What is Critical Environmental Justice?, 1st ed., Polity, Cambridge, UK, Medford, MA, USA, 2017. Riessman, C. K.: Narrative Methods for the Human Sciences, SAGE Publications Ltd, London, UK, 2008. Rivera, N.: Comunicado a la comunidad nacional e internacional. Asamblea de Pueblos Te Txe Chman, San Marcos, Prensa Comunitaria Km. 169, available at: https://comunitariapress. wordpress.com/tag/mam/ (last access: 29 April 2019), 2016. Schlosberg, D.: Defining Environmental Justice: Theories, Move- ments, and Nature, 1st ed., Oxford University Press, USA, Ox- ford, 2009. Sosa, M. and Camey-Huz, L.: Guatemal: del despojo a la gestación de alternativas, Revista Geonordeste, XXVI, 328–343, 2015. Svampa, M.: Fronteras del neoextractivismo en América Latina Conflictos socioambientales, giro ecoterritorial y nuevas depen- dencias, Maria Sybilla Merian Center. Ed. Universitaria y UCR, FLACSO Ecuador, Germany, 2019. Tamboukou, M.: A Foucauldian approach to narratives, in: Doing Narrative Research, edited by: Andrews, M., Squire, C., and Tamboukou, M., 102–120, SAGE Publications, London, UK, Thousand Oaks, California, 2013. Toledo Pineda, M. A. C. and Coraza de los Santos, E.: Los mam de México y Guatemala: un pueblo binacional entre la autonomía y la heteronomía, Revista Pueblos Y Fronteras Digital, 14, 1–32, https://doi.org/10.22201/cimsur.18704115e.2019.v14.369, 2019. Veldman, R. G., Szasz, A., and Haluza-DeLay, R.: How the World’s Religions are Responding to Climate Change: Social Scientific Investigations, Routledge, New York, NY, USA, Canada, 2013. Geogr. Helv., 75, 403–414, 2020 https://doi.org/10.5194/gh-75-403-2020 https://doi.org/10.1002/wcc.268 https://doi.org/10.1215/00382876-3749326 https://doi.org/10.5752/P.2175-5841.2010v8n17p45 https://doi.org/10.1177/0094582X15579909 https://doi.org/10.1016/S0186-6028(13)71002-8 https://www.bbc.com/mundo/noticias-america-latina-48186820 https://www.bbc.com/mundo/noticias-america-latina-48186820 https://doi.org/10.1016/j.acso.2017.08.007 https://comunitariapress.wordpress.com/tag/mam/ https://comunitariapress.wordpress.com/tag/mam/ https://doi.org/10.22201/cimsur.18704115e.2019.v14.369 Abstract Introduction Social movements as socio-environmental struggles in Latin American contexts: the eco-territorial turn Theoretical and methodological remarks Climate justice and the religion factor in socio-environmental struggles The religious and climatic elements in MODEVITE and the Council of Maya Mam narratives of struggle Climate-justice narratives emerging in MODEVITE and the Council of Maya Mam Two countries, one ethnic origin: the ancestral territory of the Maya Mam between Chiapas (Mexico) and San Marcos (Guatemala) Discussion and conclusions Data availability Supplement Competing interests Acknowledgements Review statement References work_betwehdt6vdgvdacekormu4koq ---- EP328529_for web.qxd http://epx.sagepub.com/ Educational Policy http://epx.sagepub.com/content/23/1/216 The online version of this article can be found at: DOI: 10.1177/0895904808328529 2009 23: 216Educational Policy John S. Rogers and Veronica Terriquez ''More Justice'' : The Role of Organized Labor in Educational Reform Published by: http://www.sagepublications.com On behalf of: Politics of Education Association can be found at:Educational PolicyAdditional services and information for http://epx.sagepub.com/cgi/alertsEmail Alerts: http://epx.sagepub.com/subscriptionsSubscriptions: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navReprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navPermissions: http://epx.sagepub.com/content/23/1/216.refs.htmlCitations: at UNIV CALIFORNIA BERKELEY LIB on November 5, 2010epx.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://epx.sagepub.com/ http://epx.sagepub.com/content/23/1/216 http://www.sagepublications.com http://www.fsu.edu/~pea/ http://epx.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts http://epx.sagepub.com/subscriptions http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav http://epx.sagepub.com/content/23/1/216.refs.html http://epx.sagepub.com/ “More Justice” The Role of Organized Labor in Educational Reform John S. Rogers Veronica Terriquez University of California, Los Angeles This article explores the potential role of low-wage service sector unions in engaging in equity-minded school reform. The members of many such unions are parents of children attending poorly resourced public schools. In seeking to address the interests of their members, labor unions can draw upon resources, organizing strategies, and political relationships to contribute to grassroots campaigns for educational equity. Data gathered in Los Angeles from labor and civic leaders, as well as janitors belonging to the Service Employees International Union Local 1877, reveal possibilities for low-wage service sector unions to build alliances around educational reform issues and support their members’ individual capacities to advocate for their own children in schools. At the same time, low-wage service sector unions face challenges to participating in school reform efforts, including prioritizing education issues among other competing interests and identifying common ground with teachers’ unions. Keywords: labor, organizing; school reform; equity [When the] SEIUs, the HEREs of the world . . . get involved [in educa- tional reform] it sends a different message than your traditional bargaining units who simply are involved around the bread-and-butter issues of pay [and] health care and don’t ever . . . really talk about issues of educational equity and access. . . . [The service sector] unions have a different say because their kids attend the schools. Luis Sanchez, school board staff member Educational Policy Volume 23 Number 1 January 2009 216-241 © 2009 Corwin Press 10.1177/0895904808328529 http://epx.sagepub.com hosted at http://online.sagepub.com 216 Authors’ Note: Research for this article was supported by the University of California Labor and Employment Research Fund and the Institute for Research on Labor and Employment at the University of California, Los Angeles. The authors would like to thank Ramon Martinez and Rema Reynolds for research assistance on this article. at UNIV CALIFORNIA BERKELEY LIB on November 5, 2010epx.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://epx.sagepub.com/ Let’s say a [service union] local that had X number of members in a par- ticular school called a meeting of the union . . . [and used] that already existing network and . . . community of interests between those workers at a school. They could then work with the teachers and other workers at that school, as well as other parents. They could be a bulwark for organizing parents within that school. Joel Jordan, teacher union organizer The [service sector] unions are made up of [thousands of] people. So if you can put that number of people in the streets on an issue, then you can get somebody’s attention and . . . maintain that attention until [you] get what [you] want. Goldie Buchanon, parent organizer1 Low-wage service sector unions have rarely garnered the attention of educational officials, civic elites engaged in educational reform, or scholars of the politics of education. Yet there is some reason to believe that change is afoot. During the past 15 years, service sector unions in several cities have demonstrated a willingness and capacity to mount substantial political campaigns to enhance the position of workers and improve public services. Although, to date, they have not moved in force into education policy, low-wage service sector unions hold a distinct set of educational interests, maintain considerable political resources, and have the capacity to deploy innovative and potentially powerful tactics. This article draws on data collected in Los Angeles to explore the potential for these unions to become an advocacy force to reckon with in 21st century politics of education. Consider the case of the janitors union in Los Angeles, the Service Employees International Union (SEIU) Local 1877. The vast majority of the 8,000 members of SEIU Local 1877 are immigrants with relatively low levels of formal educational attainment. In a membership survey from 2006, more than nine in ten respondents reported they were born outside of the United States, mostly in Mexico, El Salvador, and Guatemala. Only one in four members indicated that they hold a high school degree. Most of these janitors are parents of students in Los Angeles schools. And like many low-wage workers in Los Angeles, members of Local 1877 view their children’s education as the key to long-term financial security for their families. In a survey conducted by the union, three in four janitors reported that they expect their children to graduate from college. These high aspirations are not matched by quality learning opportunities for the children of Local 1877. The relatively high levels of residential seg- regation among Local 1877 members mean that many janitors send their Rogers, Terriquez / Organized Labor and Educational Reform 217 at UNIV CALIFORNIA BERKELEY LIB on November 5, 2010epx.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://epx.sagepub.com/ 218 Educational Policy children to a fairly small group of schools. Approximately half of Local 1877’s members live near 17 of Los Angeles County’s 180 comprehensive high schools.2 In Los Angeles County, as in many economically and racially segregated metropolitan areas, residential location is correlated with the resources available in local schools (Orfield & Eaton, 1996). The 17 high schools closest to Local 1877 members are highly segregated; Latino and African American students compose 90% or more of the popu- lation in 14 of the schools. In 15 of the 17 schools, more than half of the students are eligible for free or reduced-price lunch. Furthermore, these 17 schools provide notably less resources than other public schools in California. They are five times more likely than other schools in the state to experience severe shortages of qualified teachers. They are seven times more likely to be designated by the state as “critically overcrowded.” It is thus not surprising that these high schools have low graduation and college eligibility rates. For every 100 students who entered these 17 high schools in fall 2001, fewer than half graduated four years later and less than one in six graduated having completed the requirements for four-year colleges.3 This poor performance is not the exclusive domain of high schools. We estimate that more than two in three of the public schools attended by children of Local 1877 members have been designated by the state of California as Program Improvement Schools because of the schools’ fail- ure to meet adequate yearly progress as specified by the No Child Left Behind Act.4 Given the conditions and performance of public schools serving janitors’ families, it is not surprising that Local 1877 organizer Aida Cardenas calls educational reform “the civil rights issue . . . of our generation.” Cardenas’s claim is echoed by members of Local 1877. More than two in three members surveyed by the union strongly agreed with the statement “Local 1877 should become involved in improving the education system for members children.” Fewer than 5% of members disagreed, even though a number of members do not themselves have children. Furthermore, when asked to select the most important issue for the union to focus on (beyond wages, benefits, and work site concerns), Local 1877 members chose education reform above other critical issues such as immigration reform and access to affordable housing. The interest of members in educational reform is significant because Local 1877 (formerly part of Local 399) has a history of joining and winning polit- ical campaigns. In the late 1980s and 1990s, the so-called Justice for Janitors campaigns challenged both the building owners and contractors and the at UNIV CALIFORNIA BERKELEY LIB on November 5, 2010epx.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://epx.sagepub.com/ Rogers, Terriquez / Organized Labor and Educational Reform 219 conventional wisdom that immigrant workers in a decentralized, deunionizing industry could not be organized. These campaigns drew on new strategies of mass mobilization and coalition building with a variety of civic and religious groups. Local 1877 also deployed highly visible organizing tactics including public protests and marches, acts of civil disobedience (e.g., blocking traffic during Los Angeles rush hour), street theater, hunger strikes, and aggressive efforts to garner media attention. The janitors won union recognition, won improved wages and benefits, and garnered substantial political influence in the city at large (Milkman, 2006; Waldinger et al., 1998). Local 1877’s victory has been characterized as “the single most important organizing success story of the US labour movement in the late twentieth century” (Erickson, Fisk, Milkman, Mitchell, & Wong, 2002, p. 544). Yet for all of this potential, Local 1877 is only beginning to explore its role in educational reform in Los Angeles. With the notable exception of the teachers union, most sectors of organized labor have played little or no role in shaping Los Angeles educational policy and practice during the past two decades. The United Teachers of Los Angeles (or UTLA) has been the primary voice of labor on education policy issues. The only other union that consistently participates in educational policy discussions is the Associated Administrators of Los Angeles (AALA). However, AALA’s influence pales in comparison to that of UTLA. Some other unions, particularly those in the building and trades sector, have joined policy discussions about career and technical education that they see affecting workforce development. Finally, SEIU Local 99, representing classified staff in the Los Angeles Unified School District (LAUSD), has been a significant force in its own contract negotiations with the district. But it has yet to assert a formal role in discussions about educational practice. There are many reasons why educational reform has been the near exclu- sive domain of teachers unions. Many service sector unions defer educational questions to teachers unions as an acknowledgement of professional exper- tise. Local 1877 organizer Aida Cardenas explained the prevailing view has been “that’s their field, that’s their expertise, they’re the ones that know.” In addition, low-wage service sector unions generally have focused their energies on bread-and-butter concerns with salary, benefits, and working conditions or on other issues such as immigrant rights. In the remainder of this article, we explore the possibilities for service sector unions to become significant players in educational reform. We con- sider, as well, the potential significance of such a shift for organized labor, equity educational reform, and grassroots mobilization for social justice. at UNIV CALIFORNIA BERKELEY LIB on November 5, 2010epx.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://epx.sagepub.com/ This article unfolds in four sections. The first section builds a case for why organized power is necessary to promote equity reform. The second section examines the potential role of organized labor in creating organized power for educational reform. This section draws on cross-national research on social justice unionism, focus groups with Los Angeles residents, and interviews with labor and civic leaders in Los Angeles to consider the rationale and possibilities for labor-community partnerships for educational justice. The third section returns to the story of Local 1877 in the form of a case study examining the emerging educational activism of individual members and the incipient efforts to forge coordinated action. The fourth section takes a more sober note, considering the challenges of engaging low-wage service sector unions in educational reform. We close with a few thoughts on the prospects for organized labor to surmount these challenges. Our study draws on qualitative and quantitative data collected between 2006 and 2008. We conducted 11 interviews with labor and civic leaders in Los Angeles about the role of service sector unions in educational reform. The labor leaders represented such diverse constituencies as teachers, carpen- ters, janitors, and school cafeteria workers. We also gathered individual interview data from Local 1877 staff and rank-and-file 1877 leaders and conducted 40 in-depth interviews with 1877 members on their labor union involvement, parental school participation, and interest in union sponsored educational programming. We use data from two focus groups with union members regarding Local 1877’s role in supporting the education of members and their children. Furthermore, we draw on field notes gathered from our participation in the union’s education-related meetings, observations of the union’s public actions, and participant observations of nine days of parent education workshops targeting Local 1877 members with children. We also report data from two different surveys with 1877 members. The first survey was administered by the union (with our technical assistance) between November 2006 and January 2007 to 386 members at various job sites and at the union hall. The purpose of this initial survey was to gauge member interest in school reform and various education-related program- ming. In summer 2007, we conducted a telephone survey of a random sample of union members with children.5 Our survey contains a sample of 378 respondents—221 women (58%) and 157 men (42%).6 Data collected from this second survey include information on members’ demographic background, labor union participation, involvement in the school of one randomly selected school-aged child, and other information. 220 Educational Policy at UNIV CALIFORNIA BERKELEY LIB on November 5, 2010epx.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://epx.sagepub.com/ Rogers, Terriquez / Organized Labor and Educational Reform 221 Why Equity Educational Reform Requires Organized Power In the past few years, we have joined our colleague Jeannie Oakes in arguing that the problems facing urban school systems such as Los Angeles cannot adequately be addressed through conventional reform strategies that deemphasize politics and advocacy and highlight organizational change and technical expertise (Oakes & Rogers, 2006, 2007; Oakes, Rogers, Blasi, & Lipton, in press; Rogers & Oakes, 2005).7 Such strategies are dominated by three flawed assumptions. The first holds that high-quality and equitable schools can be created by working exclusively within the educational system. The second is that inequalities are sustained by a lack of informa- tion about education opportunities or appropriate reform technologies. The third assumption, following from the first two, is that once policy makers and educators understand the problem and how to address it, they will act to improve and equalize schooling. All of these assumptions presume that poor and unequal schooling is at odds with deeply held values of opportunity and fairness. Rather than conflicting with our cultural values, inequality is endemic to the logic of our society and to the role schools play in it. At least three powerful cultural “logics” shape how people make sense of the schooling that society provides to various groups of students: the logic of scarcity, the logic of merit, and the logic of deficits. The logic of scarcity assumes that our society can afford only limited investments in public life and public education. Hence, the supply of “quality” schooling cannot keep pace with increased demands for more and better education that is needed for good jobs and middle-class lives. The logic of merit assumes that young people compete for scarce schooling advantages with their talents and effort in a context of equal opportunity and are rewarded with educational opportunities commensurate with the degree to which they deserve them. The logic of deficits presumes that low-income children, children of color, and their families are limited by cultural, situational, and individual deficits that schools cannot alter. That these children get fewer education and social advantages is a result of these deficits and not of structures within the educational system. Together, these three narratives make it difficult for Americans to see that inequality is the result of flawed policies and structures rather than attributes of individual children and their families. In other words, limited opportuni- ties, educational “winners” and “losers,” and unalterable deficits all make inequality seem sensible and normal to people across political and socioeco- nomic spectra. This normalization of the status quo eases public pressure for at UNIV CALIFORNIA BERKELEY LIB on November 5, 2010epx.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://epx.sagepub.com/ equity reform. There is no need to challenge powerful vested interests or to leverage new resources (let alone redistribute existing resources) if prevailing outcomes are reasonable and inevitable. Parents and community members may express frustration with educational conditions, but not in a manner that prompts sustained political response. The logics of scarcity, merit, and deficit thus support a quiescent (though often dissatisfied) public. Altering the politics of education requires confronting these logics and energizing members of the public who are poorly served by existing schools. And this points to the importance of grassroots mobilizing to achieve more equitable schooling. Grassroots and activist organizations, seeking to build the power of low-income communities, engage students, parents, and community members in powerful actions aimed at exposing and disrupting schooling inequalities. These groups routinely target the prejudices and politics that sustain unequal schooling. Because grassroots “reformers” are also those who experience the broad range of social, economic, and political inequality, their centrality in reform forces the connections between education and broader social issues and struggles. Organized grassroots groups often use a repertoire of social movement actions—actions that persuade with the weight of their numbers, their capac- ity for material damage, and the garnering of sympathy and support by bear- ing witness (Della Porta & Diani, 1999). Actions based on the power of numbers include marches, rallies, petitions, letter writing, and mobilizing voters. Like democratic political processes, such actions attempt to persuade elites that there is large public support for or against a particular policy. Actions reflecting a theory of “material damage” include boycotts, strikes, blocking traffic, disrupting business, and, at the extreme end, damage to prop- erty. The theory here is that actions will be powerful and persuasive if they cause some noticeable impact on the economy or disrupt normal processes. Actions based on “bearing witness” include forms of civil disobedience such as hunger strikes, burning draft cards, refusal to pay taxes, and chaining one- self to a tree. These strategies seek “to demonstrate a strong commitment to an objective deemed vital for humanity’s future” by engaging in behaviors that involve personal risk or cost (Della Porta & Diani, 1999, p. 178). Together, these actions enable grassroots groups to leverage their size, networks of support, and moral standing to secure resources and forge empowered relationships with public officials. During the past decade, we have seen a significant growth in both grass- roots community organizing for educational reform and in studies of this emerging phenomena (Warren, in press). Scholars from the disciplines of sociology, political science, and education have examined struggles for 222 Educational Policy at UNIV CALIFORNIA BERKELEY LIB on November 5, 2010epx.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://epx.sagepub.com/ educational justice as a strategy for equity educational reform and civic engagement (Noguera, Ginwright, & Cammarota, 2006; Orr, 2007; Warren, 2001). Much of this literature (e.g., Shirley, 2002) has focused on community- and/or faith-based organizations as the primary agents for building power and effecting policy changes. Aside from an occasional reference to teachers unions, little attention has been paid to the potential role of labor unions in grassroots campaigns for educational reform.8 The importance of organized labor has been a more salient theme in the literature on education and social movements. In her seminal book Radical Possibilities, Jean Anyon (2005) argued that, because the problems of urban schools are embedded in the political economy of cities, lasting and signif- icant changes in educational opportunity require radical changes outside of schools, which in turn demand broad-based social movements. Anyon envisioned an important role for progressive labor unions in building such a movement (p. 160). Jeannie Oakes and John Rogers (2006, p. 172; also see Oakes et al., in press) similarly argued that the best possibility for advancing educational justice lies in social movements that simultaneously address the need for quality schooling and the needs for decent paying jobs, access to health care and housing, and so on. Oakes and Rogers hypothe- sized that the renewed focus on organizing within sectors of the labor move- ment with a large presence of working mothers may create opportunities for movement activity that brings together organized labor and community- based organizations focused on educational reform. Social Justice Unionism, Organized Power, and Educational Reform Although scholars in the field of labor studies have not yet addressed the potential of service sector unions to participate in educational reform, they have written more generally about efforts of organized labor to forge coali- tions with community organizations to address the needs of working people. For example, Frege, Heery, and Turner (2003) documented an array of coalitions in Germany, Britain, and the United States “between trade unions and other nonlabor institutions in civil society, including commu- nity, faith, identity, advocacy, welfare and campaigning organizations.” Labor scholars term such coalition-based activity social movement union- ism to highlight the importance of collective mobilization to “wrest conces- sions from corporations and corporate-dominated governments” (Nissen, 2004, p. 67). Rogers, Terriquez / Organized Labor and Educational Reform 223 at UNIV CALIFORNIA BERKELEY LIB on November 5, 2010epx.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://epx.sagepub.com/ 224 Educational Policy Social movement unionism has emerged against the backdrop of global- ization and neoliberal economics, which have combined in recent decades to erode the welfare state and shrink union membership. Union member- ship has declined from 35% of the U.S. workforce in the 1950s to less than 15% today (Fine, 2005, p. 153). During much of this period of decline, labor organizations adopted more conservative goals and tactics. They embraced top-down organizing campaigns with minimal participation from rank-and-file members, practiced nonconfrontational tactics, and, with few exceptions (e.g., in the public sector), did not engage in extensive efforts to organize new members (Milkman & Voss, 2004; Voss & Sherman, 2000). Faced with harsher conditions and declining power, some unions have responded to the crisis in labor by combining new organizing strategies with the radical tactics used in the 1930s when the U.S. labor movement was at its strongest. Unions, especially those representing workers in indus- tries that cannot be outsourced, have increasingly used massive street demonstrations, direct action, worker mobilizations, and sophisticated cam- paigns to garner more strength and power. Stepped up activism by unions was strongly supported by a turnover in leadership in the AFL-CIO in 1995. John Sweeney, the newly elected president, called for unions to use 30% of their resources for new organizing. Resulting changes have led to the revi- talization of segments of the labor movement, greater emphasis on the lead- ership development of rank-and-file workers in some unions, and increased visibility of worker mobilizations motivated by social justice, particularly in urban centers (Milkman & Voss, 2004; Voss & Sherman, 2000). This new, more militant unionism has looked to effect policy changes in nontraditional areas such as international labor standards and immigration to build its base and hence its power. These campaigns have prompted unions to seek partners outside of labor. Frege et al. (2003) explained, “As the agenda of interest representation extends beyond the immediate employ- ment relationship, unions almost inevitably become drawn into contact with preexisting campaigning and advocacy organizations.” Coalition building has the potential to revitalize unions and the broader labor movement in at least three ways. First, coalitions extend the power of unions beyond their existing membership. This potential to augment an existing base of support is critical in sectors with low union density. Second, coalitions between trade unions and community organizations around issues of public concern can foster union-friendly sentiment in the broader public. As Nissen (2004) argued, a “major task for organized labor in this country is to change the cultural climate so that union rights become a cause to which large percentages of the population are dedicated” (p. 68). Third, at UNIV CALIFORNIA BERKELEY LIB on November 5, 2010epx.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://epx.sagepub.com/ Rogers, Terriquez / Organized Labor and Educational Reform 225 participating in grassroots mobilizations generates political energy (confi- dence, commitment, and relationships) that organizers can leverage in future organizing campaigns. While acknowledging the challenges of building coalitions, labor scholars have tried to identify conditions that encourage unions to forge partnerships in the community. Tattersall and Reynolds (2007) pointed to the importance of building coalitions around a common purpose that can foster “interorga- nizational participation.” They argued that a common purpose is most effec- tive when it “is framed as a social vision for working people as a whole” (p. 79). Turner’s (2007) comparative analysis suggested that coalitions are more likely to arise in particular urban centers. Social justice unionism, he argued, emerges when key union leaders make strategic choices that take advantage of the “opportunity structure”—the institutional openings and social context (p. 4). New coalitional and grassroots strategies, for example, are particularly responsive to urban areas with sizeable service industries and a large immigrant workforce. What Can Service Sectors Unions Bring to Educational Reform? Low-wage service sector unions potentially can contribute to grassroots campaigns for educational reform through their resources, relationships, or knowledge and skills. Unions can leverage substantial resources to effect change. By pooling funds from large numbers of workers, labor unions can turn a relative weakness of low-wage workers into a relative strength. Tattersall and Reynolds’s (2007) international study of labor–community coalitions found that “out of all coalition partners, unions usually have the largest number of resources at their disposal; they usually have the largest number of members and the largest base of independent funds” (p. 78). In addition to their capacity to disperse and direct funds, many labor unions also bring a powerful communications infrastructure to campaign work. The Los Angeles School Board’s Luis Sanchez noted that unions like UNITE HERE and SEIU have “member to member capability where they can send out information to their membership, some that have 30,000 to 90,000 members. They can educate them about these issues.”9 Furthermore, by mobilizing a sizeable membership, unions can generate a prized political resource—high levels of participation in campaigns. Several Los Angeles labor and civic leaders noted the potential for unions to bring out large numbers of members to grassroots actions. UTLA’s Joel Jordan envisioned service sector unions underwriting the efforts of existing educational reform groups: at UNIV CALIFORNIA BERKELEY LIB on November 5, 2010epx.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://epx.sagepub.com/ 226 Educational Policy There are community-based organizations that help parents get organized, but they . . . don’t have the resources that many of these unions have, both in terms of staff and in terms of their overall resources. . . . So the unions could play a very valuable role. Along with activating resources, low-wage service sector unions can use their extensive social and political relationships to contribute to campaigns for educational reform. Tattersall and Reynolds (2007) argued that within social movement unionism, organized labor often draws on the social net- works of both members and unions to “enfranchise the coalition’s agenda” (p. 78). Union locals such as Local 1877, with long histories of working with community groups, are able to bring new partners into campaigns. Moreover, they can draw on existing networks with elected officials. According to SEIU’s Aida Cardenas, these networks create “political lever- age, political clout [that can] . . . help put issues on a platform or actually have some sort of decision-making power.” Low-wage service sector unions also contribute valuable knowledge and skills to their coalitional work. This contribution is noteworthy because it inverts the commonly held view that community groups provide the “brains” and unions the “muscle.” Indeed, the literature on union–commu- nity coalitions speaks of unions turning to community groups for expertise on policy issues but does not highlight the understanding that unions bring to these partnerships (Frege et al., 2003). Many service sector unions bring sophisticated understandings of organizing and campaign development that can be of great use to educational reform efforts. Aida Cardenas pointed out that at SEIU “we know how to build a base and we know . . . how to build a program and engage and give members ownership.” UTLA’s Alex Caputo- Pearl similarly argued that SEIU and UNITE HERE can teach education organizers about “tactics and approaches used in one-on-ones, leadership development, [and issues such as] how to deal with people’s fear.” Los Angeles Deputy Mayor Larry Frank was particularly expansive in his explanation of the special knowledge that unions such as SEIU and UNITE HERE bring to political work: These unions have the ability to implement something called a strategic cam- paign. This approach analyzes the political landscape, understands leverage, and can move a very large public campaign using multiple strategies. Their message and actual work is by design focused on a broad public benefit, instead of a narrow private interest. at UNIV CALIFORNIA BERKELEY LIB on November 5, 2010epx.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://epx.sagepub.com/ UTLA member Alex Caputo-Pearl made a related point in acknowledging the ability of SEIU and UNITE HERE to integrate research into their cam- paigns. These unions are able to “identify what some broader trends are going to be in the economy and industry” and how these trends “might shape schooling.” Caputo-Pearl believed these and similar insights are “really critical” for future educational campaigns. Alongside the skills embodied in a union’s staff are the skills that activist unions instill in their membership. Unions that engage members in con- tentious political activity provide members with specific advocacy and organizing skills that they can apply to other contexts outside of a labor- related campaigns. For example, workers in unions learn how to exercise their rights, file grievances, organize strikes or other collective actions, and appeal to government officials. McAdam, Tarrow, and Tilly (2001) explain that experience with activism provides participants with scripts or reper- toires. In applying these repertoires to problems they face, individuals “do not simply invent an efficient new action or express whatever impulses they feel, but rework routines in response to current circumstances” (p. 138). Participation in labor unions can be an empowering experience that shapes individuals’ interests and values. Labor unions can provide workers opportu- nities to learn about their rights and how to exercise them individually or collectively in both the workplace and in other civic arenas. Moreover, as Anyon (2005) explained, experiences such as protesting, marching, and making political demands can shape an individual’s political identity and commitments. In particular, union members’ collective participation in mili- tant workplace activities can influence their political consciousness, attitudes, and values (Fantasia, 1989). Prior experience in labor organizations that engage workers in interest-based social and political activism thus may lend itself to future activism in the arena of educational politics. Why Service Sector Unions Have a Stake in Education Reform Traditionally, unions have represented the interests of workers at the workplace, seeking to secure decent wages, benefits, and work conditions. Local 1877’s Aida Cardenas noted that her union seeks “to stabilize your job, to make it full-time, to have health insurance, to have vacations, to have a livable wage.” She called these core conditions the “basics of bringing folks out of poverty.” During the past two decades, some unions have begun to define workers’ interests more broadly. Saira Soto, staff member at Local 721 representing public sector service workers, explained that SEIU looks Rogers, Terriquez / Organized Labor and Educational Reform 227 at UNIV CALIFORNIA BERKELEY LIB on November 5, 2010epx.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://epx.sagepub.com/ “at our members as a whole, because . . . at 5:00 they go home and belong to a community that is affected by low wage work [and] the lack of affordable housing.” Unions thus have an interest, reasoned UTLA’s Joel Jordan, “in improving the overall quality of life” of their members. Beyond the workplace, low-wage service workers’ lives are shaped by policies that determine both the short-term and long-term opportunities for their families. Issues such as access to decent affordable housing speak to workers’ present needs. Immigration reform has been a critical issue for many low-wage workers because it potentially addresses both immediate threats to their livelihood and future possibilities for economic mobility and political power (Wong & Munoz, 2004). Education primarily represents a long-term interest of low-wage service workers.10 Aida Cardenas argued that although successful union campaigns can provide low-wage service workers with marginal increases in income and benefits, they cannot move families into the middle class: “So now, we’re looking at how do we really look at the next step for the future for those families, which is their . . . children’s education.” Cardenas believed that Local 1877 members see a direct rela- tionship between these educational aspirations and their daily work. It is why they work so hard every night and fight for decent working condi- tions and being rewarded for their work, so that they can provide something for their kids and their kids to go onto college and get a degree and have a much better life than they’ve lived. It is important to consider the institutional interests of the unions along- side the interests of their members. Unions want to expand their member- ship and build their power and influence. Progressive unions also want to effect social change on behalf of their members. There is an iterative rela- tionship between these two sets of interests: Struggling for and achieving social change can help unions become more powerful. In his cross-national study of unions participating in coalitions, Lowell Turner (2007) found that “unions build on bases in society well beyond the workplace to gain public support and build new political power that can also feed back into work- place power” (p. 4). Turner’s conclusion resonates with the findings from a series of focus groups convened by the Institute for Industrial Relations of the University of California, Los Angeles (UCLA) in 2005 to explore the public’s attitudes toward labor. A random sample of eligible voters in Los Angeles County reported generally unfavorable views about organized labor. Most partici- pants in the focus groups—including union members themselves—viewed 228 Educational Policy at UNIV CALIFORNIA BERKELEY LIB on November 5, 2010epx.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://epx.sagepub.com/ Rogers, Terriquez / Organized Labor and Educational Reform 229 unions as acting in narrowly self-interested ways that often undermined public purposes, for example, by protecting “bad” workers from being fired. Although a sense of indifference or hostility to unions pervaded the focus groups, these attitudes changed when focus group facilitators shared specific examples of unions standing up for nonmember workers. The examples were most persuasive when there was an explanation given for why unions might be working on issues beyond the workplace; for example, union members are parents of children in public schools (UCLA, Institute of Industrial Relations, 2006). Los Angeles Deputy Mayor Larry Frank made a related argument about the interests of service sector unions in Los Angeles: There are two primary goals that unions must address to build their political power. The first is focused on getting back their moral authority and the sec- ond is their need to organize the unaffiliated workers. For the new labor movement, those two interests are interlinked in order to get the power to be meaningful in the public arena. They need union density to elevate their voice. And they need moral authority, which comes form a focus on public benefit, to build their base. For Aida Cardenas, these dual goals represent an “opportunity” for the union “to demonstrate leadership.” Cardenas believed that, by partnering with community organizations around issues like educational reform, SEIU establishes credibility and a base of good will. As SEIU takes on big social issues, it gains “visibility within the community” which can “help us orga- nize tomorrow.” Cardenas concluded, “If a union organizer from SEIU comes out selling a tour about organizing with SEIU, it helps. So I’m think- ing the full circle.” The Case of Local 1877 Turner (2007, p. 6) highlighted two factors that shape whether coalitions between unions and community groups emerge—(a) the opportunity structure set by a particular political, economic, and institutional context and (b) the agentive decisions of key union leaders and membership. Opportunity struc- ture refers to strategic openings created by shifts in who holds authority and legitimacy or who can leverage political resources. Such openings might be created by divisions among a city’s power brokers or rapid demographic change. Agency refers to the choice of leaders to take advantage of these new opportunities. Tattersall (2006) built on Turner’s work to argue that a union’s agency is shaped by its historic identity. She is worth quoting at length: at UNIV CALIFORNIA BERKELEY LIB on November 5, 2010epx.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://epx.sagepub.com/ Unions with a history of militancy, ideological radicalism or broad interest representation beyond wages and conditions may be more likely to engage in future collaboration. Ideologically progressive unions may find it easier to cultivate a common interest with community organizations if they are com- mitted to campaigning on issues beyond wages or conditions. Similarly, if union collaboration is a familiar tactic—part of a union’s “repertoire of contention”—then it is more likely to be used as a strategy in the future. Opportunity Structure for Union Engagement in Educational Reform Four strategic openings have emerged in recent years that create an envi- ronment conducive to union–community partnerships for educational reform in Los Angeles: (a) the election of union-friendly Latino leadership in City Hall and in the school district, (b) the rise of progressive leadership in the teachers union, (c) the power of the County Federation of Labor, and (d) the residential concentration of union members around particular public schools. A first element of Los Angeles’s opportunity structure is the emergence of city and school board officials with strong ties to the low-wage service sector unions. Antonio Villaraigosa, Los Angeles’s first Latino mayor in more than a century, has deep labor roots as a former UTLA labor orga- nizer. He was elected with a tidal wave of support from immigrant and service sector workers who remain core to his coalition. Monica Garcia, the school board president, has cultivated a strong relationship with several service sector locals. She aggressively sought out the endorsement of SEIU and subsequently championed a board resolution that provided health ben- efits to cafeteria workers represented by SEIU Local 99. Second, Los Angeles’s opportunity structure is shaped by the presence of a progressive teachers union. In 2005, an insurgent slate of candidates swept the key executive offices at UTLA. This group of leaders was elected to another three-year term in February 2008. Perhaps equally important, the progressive slate (“united action”) has scored victories at the local level as well, winning more than 80% of the seats of the regional leadership of the union, all of which are held by full-time classroom teachers (A. Caputo- Pearl, personal communication, February 24, 2008). A key initiative of the new UTLA leadership has been to initiate outreach to organizations in low- income communities of color. For more than a year, UTLA has convened meetings with 10 different community groups. As Caputo-Pearl noted, “The model is there to bring other unions in . . . who want to get really involved in educational reform discussions.” 230 Educational Policy at UNIV CALIFORNIA BERKELEY LIB on November 5, 2010epx.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://epx.sagepub.com/ Rogers, Terriquez / Organized Labor and Educational Reform 231 Third, the Los Angeles County Federation of Labor plays a major role in shaping opportunities for union activism and labor-community partner- ships in Los Angeles. Representing more than 345 affiliates and 800,000 workers, the “County Fed” is a major force in Los Angeles’s economy and political life (Frank & Wong, 2004, p. 156). Since the mid-1990s, the County Fed has convened different sectors of organized labor and brokered coalitions among labor and community organizations (Frank & Wong, 2004, p. 171). It has leveraged union power to advance the candidacy of several key elected officials and, in turn, been able to call on these officials to support labor friendly policies. As UTLA’s Alex Caputo-Pearl pointed out, the County Fed’s leadership is committed to building a “broader social movement for economic and social justice.” In addition to providing an infrastructure that supports social movement unionism, the County Fed is particularly responsive to those low-wage service sector unions that might consider becoming engaged in educational reform. Finally, the intense segregation of Los Angeles’s communities by race, immigrant status, and income creates residential concentrations of union members in areas around particular public schools. For example, Local 1877 members are residentially concentrated in a handful of predomi- nantly low-income Latino communities in Los Angeles County. Figure 1 shows the residential concentration of Local 1877 members in the Los Angeles Unified elementary school catchment areas. The map indicates that more than 50 Local 1877 members live within the attendance bound- aries of 11 Los Angeles Unified elementary schools, whereas between 25 and 49 union members live within the boundaries of about 26 elementary schools. Although not all Local 1877 members have children attending local elementary schools, such geographic concentration can potentially create opportunities for parents to join with fellow union members to advocate for school reform, especially given that many already have the skills useful for school-based problem solving and parent organizing. We emphasize potential participation because most members do not yet know whether other union members send their children to the same school as their own children. Local 1877 members are scattered across different work sites throughout Los Angeles County, and union functions provide limited opportunities for members to get to know each other as parents. Yet the opportunity for parents at the same school to collaborate with each other could be realized if the union made a concerted effort to help establish school-based networks of members. at UNIV CALIFORNIA BERKELEY LIB on November 5, 2010epx.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://epx.sagepub.com/ 232 Educational Policy Figure 1 Residential Concentration of Local 1877 Members in Los Angeles Unified School District (LAUSD) Elementary School Attendance Boundaries at UNIV CALIFORNIA BERKELEY LIB on November 5, 2010epx.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://epx.sagepub.com/ Rogers, Terriquez / Organized Labor and Educational Reform 233 Agency and Identity Since the early 1990s, SEIU Local 1877 has made headlines in Los Angeles for its successful Justice for Janitors campaigns. Throughout the years, the union has won higher wages, health care benefits, and other job protections for its largely Latino immigrant membership. Its highly visible organizing tactics include public protests and marches, acts of civil disobedi- ence (e.g., blocking traffic during the Los Angeles rush hour), street theater, hunger strikes, and aggressive efforts to garner media attention. The union’s organizing efforts have not been restricted to the five master contracts that it has negotiated within the past two decades on behalf of janitors. The union actively involves its members in immigrant rights’ demonstrations, election campaigns, and other political activities. Given the union’s past and historic efforts to engage members in its activist efforts, it is not surprising that many Local 1877 members have taken steps—on their own—to improve their children’s schools. Union members have participated in a range of school and community-based meetings focused on issues such as school overcrowding and substandard facilities. Individual Local 1877 members with children attending several different schools have reported collaborating with other parents to address student health and safety concerns at school sites. For example, when one parent found out that the drinking water at his child’s school contained lead, he initiated a successful campaign to force the school district to provide uncontaminated water. Participation in union-related activities provides many members with confidence and skills that enhance their participation in their children’s schools. Several union members report that their participation in union activism has boosted their confidence and their ability to speak up and defend themselves and others. These parents note that, in the past, they have felt uncomfortable speaking in public and confronting authority figures, including school personnel. Yet participation in union meetings, marches, trainings, and other activities has increased their assertiveness. For example, Lucia, a rank-and-file leader, stated, I was a very timid person, honestly, a very timid person. If I had to speak in public, I would turn red and would not know what to say. Getting involved in the [union] trainings has helped me become unafraid. . . . I believe that the union has played an important role in my life. I have learned a lot. It has given me confidence, it has helped me defend myself and speak to other people.11 at UNIV CALIFORNIA BERKELEY LIB on November 5, 2010epx.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://epx.sagepub.com/ 234 Educational Policy Many Local 1877 members apply skills that they learn at the union to school-based advocacy and organizing efforts. One parent participated in the union’s contract negotiations and learned negotiating skills useful for advocating for more tutoring for her son and other children. The story of Francisco, a Guatemalan immigrant with a sixth grade education, offers an example of how union experience enhances parents’ school advocacy skills. Francisco arrived in Los Angeles in the late 1980s, obtained work as a jan- itor, and soon became involved in the Justice for Janitors campaigns. By the mid-1990s, he became a union steward and learned to help coworkers solve their grievances and mobilize them for union strikes and actions. As a shop steward, Francisco was required to keep track of workers’ phone numbers and the information that they needed to resolve their problems or obtain a large turnout for a rally. Now that he is no longer the shop steward at work, he performs a similar function for parents at his children’s schools. Yes, my book over there is where I have all the numbers. I can look for it right now and tell you with whom I have spoken to, all the numbers [I have called]. And I know, for example, the big district right now is at 333 Beaudry [Los Angeles Unified District Offices]. Well then, I call over there and they are the ones that are in charge of administration for all the schools. If they don’t help, you get in touch with Sacramento, and from Sacramento, they send an investi- gation and the whole thing gets bigger. Then the schools don’t like that, not even the district, because then other problems arise, and the problems get bigger.12 Possibilities for Joint Action Under the Union’s Leadership To date, Local 1877 members have engaged in educational advocacy primarily as individual parents rather than as members of their union. Yet Local 1877 members have a long history of working together as members of the same labor organization to address specific work site problems, fight for a fair contract, and campaign for other political causes (immigrant rights, election of a labor-friendly candidate, etc.). Recently, the union has begun to respond to members’ concerns about their children’s education. For example, the union has sponsored parent education workshops that provide members with additional information and skills to advocate for their children. At the request of membership, Local 1877 began hosting “Parent University” workshops to provide its immigrant workers a better under- standing of the California public school system and the roles parents can play to support their children through the schooling process. Workshops included topics such as parent rights, school governance structures, under- standing report cards and standardized tests, the college application process, at UNIV CALIFORNIA BERKELEY LIB on November 5, 2010epx.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://epx.sagepub.com/ Rogers, Terriquez / Organized Labor and Educational Reform 235 resource inequalities in public schools, and the California education budget. These workshops provide useful information for parent advocacy efforts. For example, after learning that she and other parents had a right to trans- lation at school events, one parent successfully advocated for interpreters at all parent meetings at her child’s school. Local 1877 used its most recent round of contract negotiations in spring 2008 to further support parental school involvement. Prior to negotiations, rank-and-file members expressed concern over conflicts that sometimes emerged between their work obligations and their desire to play a more active role at their children’s schools. Many members reported that they were not given permission to leave work to attend back-to-school nights, parent conferences, and other school events. One parent was not allowed to attend her daughter’s graduation. The members thus were interested to learn that an existing state law, the California Family–School Partnership Act, guarantees parents and guardians the right to take up to 40 hours off work each year to participate in activities at a child’s school or day care facility. Recognizing that the act provided no meaningful enforcement mechanism, Local 1877’s rank-and-file members and leaders reasoned that they could realize the law’s lofty rhetoric by making specific reference to it in their labor contract. As a result, the union was able to secure a contrac- tual commitment for janitors to be able to participate in their children’s schools in accordance with the Children Family–School Partnership Act. In addition, Local 1877 conducted a Parent University training for parents on the act and created a brochure that could be disseminated to members to facilitate parental school involvement. Local 1877 has directly and indirectly supported parents’ roles in edu- cation by using the union contract to create a fund for worker education. As a result of the most recent janitors’ contract signed in spring 2008, employ- ers must now contribute three cents per hour worked per employee to pro- vide workers with English classes at the union and at various job sites. This fund is also used for computer training and citizenship courses and may in the future be used for a GED program. Significantly, it supports the Parent University workshops. Challenges to Engaging Organized Labor in Educational Reform Thus far, we have told an optimistic story about the prospects for low- wage sector unions such as Local 1877 to become engaged in educational at UNIV CALIFORNIA BERKELEY LIB on November 5, 2010epx.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://epx.sagepub.com/ reform. We have argued that these unions have a strong interest in promot- ing educational equity, that they stand to contribute substantially to such efforts, and that the political and institutional environment presents unique opportunities for them to become part of educational justice campaigns. In this section, we temper some of that optimism. We highlight ongoing com- petition for time and resources and then turn to the thorny problem of turf battles among unions. We close with a few thoughts on a way forward. A first challenge to engaging low-wage sector unions in educational reform is that these unions have many important demands on their atten- tion. Noting these multiple demands, Joel Jordan of UTLA argued that unions such as 1877 need to prioritize their goals. But, as Aida Cardenas suggested, this is no easy task. At 1877, we’re breaking through in new industries; we’re breaking through in sectors like security. We’re trying to fight through the airports, which is not an easy place especially after 9/11. We’re outreaching into other parts of the country. . . . The challenge is that we want to do a lot because there’s so much that needs to happen, so the challenge is keeping the focus; the chal- lenge is having the resources to do everything you want to do. A second, and related, challenge is that educational funding is often set in opposition to funds for other critical public services that affect low-wage workers. Union staffers such as Saira Soto face Solomonic choices about which policies to support. “There are too many things that need immediate attention so how do you push education over health care, how do you push health care over affordable housing, they are all extremely urgent and crit- ical issues.” The difficulty of these choices is compounded by state funding formulas that lock in funds for some services but not others and by the gen- eral public’s proclivity to support education spending before they support programs more directly targeted to address poverty. In times of budgetary retrenchment, it is thus difficult for low-wage service sector unions to com- mit to pursuing a narrow education agenda. The third challenge emerges from the fault lines separating teachers unions from low-wage service sector unions. In its crudest form, this sepa- ration emerges from class anxieties among teachers who worry about forg- ing alliances with low-wage workers. Hence, a delegate from the American Federation of Teachers shared his concerns about the new unionism with a New York Times reporter. “Don’t they realize if they really push this orga- nizing, the labor movement is going to wind up being a movement of straw- berry pickers and chicken pluckers?” (quoted in Early, 2004). 236 Educational Policy at UNIV CALIFORNIA BERKELEY LIB on November 5, 2010epx.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://epx.sagepub.com/ But the divisions between teachers and other workers cannot simply be explained away as class bias. UTLA has been the preeminent—and often the sole—union voice on educational policy in Los Angeles for decades. UTLA officials feel that this historic role, alongside teachers’ professional expertise, should ensure a leadership role in any collaboration. Joel Jordan of UTLA noted that he expects other unions to coordinate any education work with UTLA. It would seem like a strange form of behavior [for 1877 to move unilaterally on educational issues]. It would seem that if those people who are really interested in school reform would want to . . . talk to the teachers union and also talk to teachers at schools. . . . If I was a local union outside of the teaching—outside of the teachers union, I would certainly—if I really was interested in pursuing reform and improvement in public education, the first place I would go to would be the teachers union and to the sister SEIU local that has members inside, who actually work with kids. These tensions over turf have been exacerbated by competing under- standings of the charter school movement. UTLA’s leadership worries that some charter schools do not ensure public accountability and equitable access to all students. More pointed, the leadership views charter schools that refuse union representation to their employees as a direct threat to UTLA’s power and to organized labor generally. Joel Jordan asserted that charter schools often take funds from districts and turn them over to nonunion operators, thereby harming both the teachers union and unions representing classified staff. Meanwhile, SEIU national director Andy Stern looked on charter schools as an expanding sector of the educational market that should be organized (Seewer, 2007). Alongside this difference in perspective is the political reality that Local 1877’s president Mike Garcia sits on the board of directors of Green Dot Schools, one of the major charter operators in Los Angeles. Teachers in Green Dot Schools are represented by the California Teachers Association rather than UTLA. Green Dot’s CEO Steve Barr and UTLA president A. J. Duffy sparred frequently in the media when Green Dot first sought to establish charter schools in areas traditionally served by the LAUSD (Lewis, 2006). These disputes most often centered on the question of whether Green Dot selectively recruited students, but the issue of union power was never far from the surface. The public rancor has given way in recent months to a less conflictual relationship, as UTLA has focused its attention on the problems with nonunionized charters (Blume, 2008; Dillon, 2007). Rogers, Terriquez / Organized Labor and Educational Reform 237 at UNIV CALIFORNIA BERKELEY LIB on November 5, 2010epx.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://epx.sagepub.com/ 238 Educational Policy Prospects and Possibilities The likelihood of internecine battles within the house of labor thus seems to blunt the prospects for low-wage service sector unions to move forcefully into the field of educational reform. Deputy Mayor Larry Frank noted, “Ideally, labor is not at war with itself.” Is there a way forward? SEIU staff member Saira Soto pointed toward one helpful step. Service sector unions can begin to build bridges with the teachers union around issues of common concern. Union members whose children attend poorly resourced schools have an interest in attracting and retaining quality teachers. “Teachers should get paid more, [have] less students in a class. So there are a lot of places where we overlap in terms of what we want.” By entering into strategic alliances around such issues, low-wage service sector unions could begin to establish trust and a sense of goodwill that could lead to further partnerships. UTLA chapter chair Alex Caputo-Pearl suggested a different starting point for collaboration: focusing attention on a common enemy. “I think the biggest challenge [for] . . . unions, community organizations, or whomever is the . . . inertia and bureaucratic sort of groupthink.” He calls for a nuanced approach to charters. Although he opposes charters in principle, he under- stands that unionized charters can be used as a lever against district bureau- cracy so teachers, parents, and community groups have greater “freedom, support, resources, and time to figure out some things for themselves and not just be beholden to the next district memo.” Although there are still many issues that need to be sorted out, the poten- tial of low-wage service sector unions in educational reform represents a force to be reckoned with. This force has the capacity to build union mem- bership and enhance the moral standing of unions in the broader commu- nity. It can leverage more empowered relationships with education officials and significant new resources for poorly served schools. By connecting struggles for educational equity with other campaigns of low-income work- ers, it advances the possibility of broader social movements. Although this vision may seem millennialist, it is not new. “What does labor want?” asked Samuel Gompers in 1893. “We want more schoolhouses and less jails; more books and less arsenals; more learning and less vice; more leisure and less greed; more justice [italics added] and less revenge; in fact, more of the opportunities to cultivate our better natures”. Notes 1. Unless otherwise noted, the quotes in this article come from interviews or focus groups conducted between 2006 and 2008 with members and leaders of the Service Employee at UNIV CALIFORNIA BERKELEY LIB on November 5, 2010epx.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://epx.sagepub.com/ International Local 1877 and Los Angeles labor and community leaders. We use pseudonyms for members of Local 1877. We identify all other labor, community, and civic leaders with their real names. 2. Data on the residential concentration of Local 1877 members come from 2006 zip code data provided by the union. 3. Our analysis of the conditions and outcomes in these 17 schools draws on the annual Education Opportunity Reports that we have coauthored with our colleagues at the Institute for Democracy, Education, and Access, University of California, Los Angeles. The reports define “severe shortages of qualified teachers,” “critically overcrowded schools,” and eligibility for four-year colleges. See http://www.edopp.org. 4. This estimate is based on a 2007 random sample survey of Local 1877 members. Data about the conditions and performance of these public schools are drawn from the California Basic Educational Data System. 5. The survey was funded by the University of California Labor Employment Research Fund. The Social Science Research Center at California State University, Fullerton conducted the telephone survey. 6. The sample excludes individuals for whom updated telephone information was missing from the union’s membership list in April 2007 when the sample was drawn. Of eligible study participants, 67% completed the phone survey. Local 1877’s represents approximately 8,000 janitors and other low-wage service workers. 7. This section draws on ongoing collaborative work with Jeannie Oakes. 8. There also has been some emerging organizing efforts that bring together progressive teachers unions with grassroots community organizing groups. The Center For Community Change in Washington, D.C., has played a key role in convening and documenting such part- nerships (Dingerson, 2007). 9. In 2004, UNITE (Union of Needletrades, Industrial and Textile Employees) merged with HERE (Hotel Employees and Restaurant Employees International Union) to form UNITE HERE. 10. Education can also be said to represent an immediate interest for low-wage workers in at least two ways. First, public schools provide a set of services that affect workers’ children in the here and now (their sense of self, health, and safety). Second, language classes, adult education, and community college courses can provide workers with knowledge and skills that can be used to advance their job status. 11. This quote is translated from the original Spanish. 12. See Note 11. References Anyon, J. (2005). Radical possibilities: Public policy, urban education and a new social move- ment. New York: Routledge. Blume, H. (2008, September 19). Teachers union chief comments on Green Dot and Locke High. Los Angeles Times. Retrieved September 19, 2008, from http://latimesblogs.latimes .com/thehomeroom/2008/09/teacher-union-c.html Della Porta, D., & Diani, M. (1999). Social movements: An introduction. Oxford, UK: Blackwell. Dillon, S. (2007, July 24). Maverick leads charge for charter schools. New York Times. Retrieved September 19, 2008, from http://www.nytimes.com/2007/07/24/education/24charter.html Rogers, Terriquez / Organized Labor and Educational Reform 239 at UNIV CALIFORNIA BERKELEY LIB on November 5, 2010epx.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://epx.sagepub.com/ 240 Educational Policy Dingerson, L. (2007). Organized teachers and parents: A powerful combination. Washington, DC: Center for Community Change. Retrieved September 1, 2008 at http://www.ccc- files.org/issues/education/partners/edu_secure/downloads/partnerhips_for_change_broch ure.pdf?page=descriptions. Early, S. (2004). Reutherism redux: What happens when poor workers’ unions wear the color purple? Labor Advocate Online. Retrieved February 5, 2008 from http://www.kclabor.org/ reutherism_redux .htm. Erickson, C. L., Fisk, C. L., Milkman, R., Mitchell, D. J. B., & Wong, K. (2002). Justice for janitors in Los Angeles: Lessons from three rounds of negotiations. British Journal of Industrial Relations, 40, 543-567. Fantasia, R. (1989). Cultures of solidarity: Consciousness, action, and contemporary American workers. Berkeley: University of California Press. Fine, J. (2005). Community unions and the revival of the American labor movement. Politics and Society, 33(1), 153-199. Frank, L., & Wong, K. (2004). Dynamic political mobilization: The Los Angeles County Federation of Labor. WorkingUSA: The Journal of Labor and Society, 8, 155-181. Frege, C., Heery, E., & Turner, L. (2003, January). Comparative coalition building and the revitalization of the labor movement. Paper presented at the Industrial Relations Research Association conference, Washington, DC. http://www.press.uillinois.edu/journals/irra/ proceedings2003/frege.html Gompers, S. (1893/1989). An address before the International Labor Congress in Chicago: What does labor want? In S. Kaufman and P. Albert (Series Eds.) The Samuel Gompers Papers: Volume 3. Unrest and Depression: 1891-94. (pp. 388-96) Chicago: University of Illinois Press. Lewis, J. (2006, December 7). The secret of his success. LA Weekly. Retrieved September 19, 2008, from http://www.laweekly.com/2006-12-07/news/the-secret-of-his-success/ McAdam, D., Tarrow, S., & Tilly, C. (2001). Dynamics of contention. New York: Cambridge University Press. Milkman, R. (2006). L.A. story: Immigrant workers and the future of the U.S. labor movement. New York: Russell Sage. Milkman, R. & K. Voss. (2004). Rebuilding labor: Organizing and organizers in the new union movements. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Nissen, B. (2004). The effectiveness and limits of labor-community coalitions: Evidence from South Florida. Labor Studies Journal, 29(1), 67-89. Noguera, P., Ginwright, S. E., & Cammarota, J. (2006). Beyond resistance! Youth activism and community change: New democratic possibilities for practice and policy for America’s youth. New York: Routledge. Oakes, J., & Rogers, J. (2006). Learning power: Organizing for education and justice. New York: Teachers College Press. Oakes, J. and Rogers, J. (2007). Radical change through radical democratic means: Organizing for equitable schools. Journal of Educational Change, 8, 193-206. Oakes, J., Rogers, J., Blasi, G., & Lipton, M. (in press). Grassroots organizing, social movements, and the right to high-quality education. Stanford Journal of Civil Rights and Civil Liberties. Orfield, G. & S. Eaton. (1996). Dismantling desegregation : The quiet reversal of Brown v. Board of Education. New York, NY: New Press. Orr, M. (2007). Community organizing and the changing ecology of civic engagement. In M. Orr (Ed.), Transforming the city: Community organizing and the challenge of political change (pp. 1-27). Lawrence: University Press of Kansas. at UNIV CALIFORNIA BERKELEY LIB on November 5, 2010epx.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://epx.sagepub.com/ Rogers, J., & Oakes, J. (2005). John Dewey speaks to Brown: Research, democratic social movement strategies, and the struggle for education on equal terms. Teachers College Record, 107(9), 2178-2203. Seewer, J. (2007, April 15). Leader guides breakaway SEIU. San Mateo County Times. Retrieved November 1, 2008 from http://iw.newsbank.com/iw-search/we/InfoWeb?p_action=doc&p_ heme=aggdocs&p_topdoc=1&p_docnum=1&p_sort=YMD_date:D&p_product= AW N B & p _ d o c i d = 1 1 8 8 D 7 A 0 E 3 6 A 2 1 B 0 & p _ t e x t _ d i r e c t - 0 = d o c u m e n t _ i d = (%201188D7A0E36A21B0%20)&p_nbid=I61C61EVMTIyNjM4MTU5MS42MDgzNjQ6 MToxMDoxMjguOTcuMC4w Shirley, D. (2002). Valley interfaith and school reform: Organizing for power in south Texas. Austin: University of Texas Press. Tattersall, A. (2006). A little help from our friends: A framework for understanding when labor unions are likely to join long-term union-community coalitions. Union Ideas Network. Retrieved February 5, 2008 from http://uin.org.uk/dmdocuments/2006-10-16—23-35- tattersall%20a% 20little%20help%20from%20our%20friends%20distribute.pdf Tattersall, A., & Reynolds, D. (2007). The shifting power of labor-community coalitions: Identifying common elements of powerful coalitions in Australia and the U.S. WorkingUSA: The Journal of Labor and Society, 10(1), 77-102. Turner, L. (2007). An urban resurgence of social unionism. In L. Turner & D. Cornfield (Eds.), Labor in the new urban battlegrounds: Local solidarity in a global economy (pp. 1-20). Ithaca, NY: Cornel University Press. University of California, Los Angeles, Institute of Industrial Relations. (2006, February). Attitudes about labor unions: Los Angeles County residents. Los Angeles: Author. Voss, K., & Sherman, R. (2000). Breaking the iron law of oligarchy: Union revitalization in the American labor movement. American Journal of Sociology, 106, 303-349. Waldinger, R., Erickson, C. L., Milkman, R., Mitchell, D. J. B., Valenzuela, A., Wong, K., et al. (1998). Helots no more: A case study of the justice for janitors campaign in Los Angeles. In K. Bronfenbrenner, S. Friedman, R. W. Hurd, R. A. Oswald, & R. L. Seeber (Eds.), Organizing to win (pp. 102-119). Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Warren, M. (2001). Dry bones rattling: Community building to revitalize American democ- racy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Warren, M. (in press). Community organizing for educational reform. In M. Orr & J. Rogers (Eds.), Public engagement for public education. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press. Wong, K., & Munoz, C. (2004). Don’t miss the bus: The immigrant workers’ freedom ride. New Labor Forum, 13(2), 61-66. John Rogers is an associate professor in UCLA’s Graduate School of Educationand Information Studies and the director of UCLA's Institute for Democracy, Education and Access (IDEA).Rogers also serves as the faculty co-director of UCLA's Principal Leadership Institute. He studies public engagement and community organizing as strategies for equity- focused school reform and democratic renewal. He draws extensively on the work of John Dewey to explore the meaning of, and possibilities for, democratic education today. Veronica Terriquez is a PhD candidate in the Department of Sociology at UCLA. Her research focuses on schooling inequalities, civic engagement in schools and labor unions, and immigrant integration. Rogers, Terriquez / Organized Labor and Educational Reform 241 at UNIV CALIFORNIA BERKELEY LIB on November 5, 2010epx.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://epx.sagepub.com/ << /ASCII85EncodePages false /AllowTransparency false /AutoPositionEPSFiles true /AutoRotatePages /None /Binding /Left /CalGrayProfile (Dot Gain 20%) /CalRGBProfile (sRGB IEC61966-2.1) /CalCMYKProfile (U.S. Web Coated \050SWOP\051 v2) /sRGBProfile (sRGB IEC61966-2.1) /CannotEmbedFontPolicy /Error /CompatibilityLevel 1.3 /CompressObjects /Off /CompressPages true /ConvertImagesToIndexed true /PassThroughJPEGImages true /CreateJobTicket false /DefaultRenderingIntent /Default /DetectBlends true /DetectCurves 0.1000 /ColorConversionStrategy /LeaveColorUnchanged /DoThumbnails false /EmbedAllFonts true /EmbedOpenType false /ParseICCProfilesInComments true /EmbedJobOptions true /DSCReportingLevel 0 /EmitDSCWarnings false /EndPage -1 /ImageMemory 1048576 /LockDistillerParams true /MaxSubsetPct 100 /Optimize false /OPM 1 /ParseDSCComments true /ParseDSCCommentsForDocInfo true /PreserveCopyPage true /PreserveDICMYKValues true /PreserveEPSInfo true /PreserveFlatness true /PreserveHalftoneInfo false /PreserveOPIComments false /PreserveOverprintSettings true /StartPage 1 /SubsetFonts true /TransferFunctionInfo /Apply /UCRandBGInfo /Remove /UsePrologue false /ColorSettingsFile () /AlwaysEmbed [ true /ACaslon-Ornaments /AGaramond-BoldScaps /AGaramond-Italic /AGaramond-Regular /AGaramond-RomanScaps /AGaramond-Semibold /AGaramond-SemiboldItalic /AGar-Special /AkzidenzGroteskBE-Bold /AkzidenzGroteskBE-BoldIt /AkzidenzGroteskBE-It /AkzidenzGroteskBE-Light /AkzidenzGroteskBE-LightOsF /AkzidenzGroteskBE-Md /AkzidenzGroteskBE-MdIt /AkzidenzGroteskBE-Regular /AkzidenzGroteskBE-Super /AlbertusMT /AlbertusMT-Italic /AlbertusMT-Light /Aldine401BT-BoldA /Aldine401BT-BoldItalicA /Aldine401BT-ItalicA /Aldine401BT-RomanA /Aldine401BTSPL-RomanA /Aldine721BT-Bold /Aldine721BT-BoldItalic /Aldine721BT-Italic /Aldine721BT-Light /Aldine721BT-LightItalic /Aldine721BT-Roman /Aldus-Italic /Aldus-Roman /AlternateGothicNo2BT-Regular /Anna /AntiqueOlive-Bold /AntiqueOlive-Compact /AntiqueOlive-Italic /AntiqueOlive-Roman /Arcadia /Arcadia-A /Arkona-Medium /Arkona-Regular /AssemblyLightSSK /AvantGarde-Book /AvantGarde-BookOblique /AvantGarde-Demi /AvantGarde-DemiOblique /BakerSignetBT-Roman /BaskervilleBE-Italic /BaskervilleBE-Medium /BaskervilleBE-MediumItalic /BaskervilleBE-Regular /BaskervilleBook-Italic /BaskervilleBook-MedItalic /BaskervilleBook-Medium /BaskervilleBook-Regular /BaskervilleBT-Bold /BaskervilleBT-BoldItalic /BaskervilleBT-Italic /BaskervilleBT-Roman /BaskervilleMT /BaskervilleMT-Bold /BaskervilleMT-BoldItalic /BaskervilleMT-Italic /BaskervilleMT-SemiBold /BaskervilleMT-SemiBoldItalic /BaskervilleNo2BT-Bold /BaskervilleNo2BT-BoldItalic /BaskervilleNo2BT-Italic /BaskervilleNo2BT-Roman /Bauhaus-Bold /Bauhaus-Demi /Bauhaus-Heavy /BauhausITCbyBT-Bold /BauhausITCbyBT-Medium /Bauhaus-Light /Bauhaus-Medium /BellCentennial-Address /BellGothic-Black /BellGothic-Bold /Bell-GothicBoldItalicBT /BellGothicBT-Bold /BellGothicBT-Roman /BellGothic-Light /Bembo /Bembo-Bold /Bembo-BoldExpert /Bembo-BoldItalic /Bembo-BoldItalicExpert /Bembo-Expert /Bembo-ExtraBoldItalic /Bembo-Italic /Bembo-ItalicExpert /Bembo-Semibold /Bembo-SemiboldItalic /Berkeley-Black /Berkeley-BlackItalic /Berkeley-Bold /Berkeley-BoldItalic /Berkeley-Book /Berkeley-BookItalic /Berkeley-Italic /Berkeley-Medium /Berling-Bold /Berling-BoldItalic /Berling-Italic /Berling-Roman /BernhardModernBT-Bold /BernhardModernBT-BoldItalic /BernhardModernBT-Italic /BernhardModernBT-Roman /Bodoni /Bodoni-Bold /Bodoni-BoldItalic /Bodoni-Italic /Bodoni-Poster /Bodoni-PosterCompressed /Bookman-Demi /Bookman-DemiItalic /Bookman-Light /Bookman-LightItalic /Boton-Italic /Boton-Medium /Boton-MediumItalic /Boton-Regular /Boulevard /BremenBT-Black /BremenBT-Bold /CaflischScript-Bold /CaflischScript-Regular /Carta /Caslon224ITCbyBT-Bold /Caslon224ITCbyBT-BoldItalic /Caslon224ITCbyBT-Book /Caslon224ITCbyBT-BookItalic /Caslon540BT-Italic /Caslon540BT-Roman /CaslonBT-Bold /CaslonBT-BoldItalic /CaslonTwoTwentyFour-Black /CaslonTwoTwentyFour-BlackIt /CaslonTwoTwentyFour-Bold /CaslonTwoTwentyFour-BoldIt /CaslonTwoTwentyFour-Book /CaslonTwoTwentyFour-BookIt /CaslonTwoTwentyFour-Medium /CaslonTwoTwentyFour-MediumIt /CastleT-Bold /CastleT-Book /Caxton-Bold /Caxton-BoldItalic /Caxton-Book /Caxton-BookItalic /Caxton-Light /Caxton-LightItalic /CelestiaAntiqua-Ornaments /Centennial-BlackItalicOsF /Centennial-BlackOsF /Centennial-BoldItalicOsF /Centennial-BoldOsF /Centennial-ItalicOsF /Centennial-LightItalicOsF /Centennial-LightSC /Centennial-RomanSC /CenturyOldStyle-Bold /CenturyOldStyle-Italic /CenturyOldStyle-Regular /CheltenhamBT-Bold /CheltenhamBT-BoldItalic /CheltenhamBT-Italic /CheltenhamBT-Roman /Christiana-Bold /Christiana-BoldItalic /Christiana-Italic /Christiana-Medium /Christiana-MediumItalic /Christiana-Regular /Christiana-RegularExpert /Christiana-RegularSC /Clarendon /Clarendon-Bold /Clarendon-Light /ClassicalGaramondBT-Bold /ClassicalGaramondBT-BoldItalic /ClassicalGaramondBT-Italic /ClassicalGaramondBT-Roman /CMTI10 /CommonBullets /ConduitITC-Bold /ConduitITC-BoldItalic /ConduitITC-Light /ConduitITC-LightItalic /ConduitITC-Medium /ConduitITC-MediumItalic /CooperBlack /CooperBlack-Italic /CopperplateGothicBT-Bold /CopperplateGothicBT-BoldCond /CopperplateGothicBT-Heavy /CopperplateGothicBT-Roman /CopperplateGothicBT-RomanCond /Copperplate-ThirtyThreeBC /Copperplate-ThirtyTwoBC /Coronet-Regular /Courier /Courier-Bold /Courier-BoldOblique /Courier-Oblique /Critter /CS-Special-font /DextorD /DextorOutD /DidotLH-OrnamentsOne /DidotLH-OrnamentsTwo /DINEngschrift /DINEngschrift-Alternate /DINMittelschrift /DINMittelschrift-Alternate /DINNeuzeitGrotesk-BoldCond /DINNeuzeitGrotesk-Light /Dom-CasItalic /Dom-CasualBT /Ehrhard-Italic /Ehrhard-Regular /EhrhardSemi-Italic /EhrhardtMT /EhrhardtMT-Italic /EhrhardtMT-SemiBold /EhrhardtMT-SemiBoldItalic /EhrharSemi /ElectraLH-Bold /ElectraLH-BoldCursive /ElectraLH-Cursive /ElectraLH-Regular /EnglischeSchT-Bold /EnglischeSchT-Regu /ErasContour /ErasITCbyBT-Bold /ErasITCbyBT-Book /ErasITCbyBT-Demi /ErasITCbyBT-Light /ErasITCbyBT-Medium /ErasITCbyBT-Ultra /EUEX10 /EUFB10 /EUFB5 /EUFB7 /EUFM10 /EUFM5 /EUFM7 /EURB10 /EURB5 /EURB7 /EURM10 /EURM5 /EURM7 /EuropeanPi-Four /EuropeanPi-One /EuropeanPi-Three /EuropeanPi-Two /Eurostile /Eurostile-Bold /Eurostile-BoldExtendedTwo /Eurostile-ExtendedTwo /EUSB10 /EUSB5 /EUSB7 /EUSM10 /EUSM5 /EUSM7 /ExPonto-Regular /Fenice-Bold /Fenice-BoldOblique /FeniceITCbyBT-Bold /FeniceITCbyBT-BoldItalic /FeniceITCbyBT-Regular /FeniceITCbyBT-RegularItalic /Fenice-Light /Fenice-LightOblique /Fenice-Regular /Fenice-RegularOblique /Fenice-Ultra /Fenice-UltraOblique /FlashD-Ligh /Folio-Bold /Folio-BoldCondensed /Folio-ExtraBold /Folio-Light /Folio-Medium /FontanaNDEeOsF /FontanaNDEeOsF-Semibold /FormalScript421BT-Regular /Formata-Bold /Formata-MediumCondensed /FournierMT-Ornaments /FrakturBT-Regular /FranklinGothic-Book /FranklinGothic-BookItal /FranklinGothic-BookOblique /FranklinGothic-Condensed /FranklinGothic-Demi /FranklinGothic-DemiItal /FranklinGothic-DemiOblique /FranklinGothic-Heavy /FranklinGothic-HeavyItal /FranklinGothic-HeavyOblique /FranklinGothic-Medium /FranklinGothic-MediumItal /FranklinGothic-Roman /FrizQuadrataITCbyBT-Bold /FrizQuadrataITCbyBT-Roman /Frutiger-Black /Frutiger-BlackCn /Frutiger-BlackItalic /Frutiger-Bold /Frutiger-BoldCn /Frutiger-BoldItalic /Frutiger-Cn /Frutiger-ExtraBlackCn /Frutiger-Italic /Frutiger-Light /Frutiger-LightCn /Frutiger-LightItalic /Frutiger-Roman /Frutiger-UltraBlack /Futura /FuturaBlackBT-Regular /Futura-Bold /Futura-BoldOblique /Futura-Book /Futura-BookOblique /FuturaBT-Bold /FuturaBT-BoldCondensed /FuturaBT-BoldCondensedItalic /FuturaBT-BoldItalic /FuturaBT-Book /FuturaBT-BookItalic /FuturaBT-ExtraBlack /FuturaBT-ExtraBlackCondensed /FuturaBT-ExtraBlackCondItalic /FuturaBT-ExtraBlackItalic /FuturaBT-Heavy /FuturaBT-HeavyItalic /FuturaBT-Light /FuturaBT-LightCondensed /FuturaBT-LightItalic /FuturaBT-Medium /FuturaBT-MediumCondensed /FuturaBT-MediumItalic /Futura-ExtraBold /Futura-ExtraBoldOblique /Futura-Heavy /Futura-HeavyOblique /Futura-Light /Futura-LightOblique /Futura-Oblique /GalliardITCbyBT-Italic /GalliardITCbyBT-Roman /Garamond-Antiqua /Garamond-BoldCondensed /Garamond-BoldCondensedItalic /Garamond-BookCondensed /Garamond-BookCondensedItalic /Garamond-Halbfett /GaramondITCbyBT-Bold /GaramondITCbyBT-BoldCondensed /GaramondITCbyBT-BoldCondItalic /GaramondITCbyBT-BoldItalic /GaramondITCbyBT-BoldNarrow /GaramondITCbyBT-BoldNarrowItal /GaramondITCbyBT-Book /GaramondITCbyBT-BookCondensed /GaramondITCbyBT-BookCondItalic /GaramondITCbyBT-BookItalic /GaramondITCbyBT-Light /GaramondITCbyBT-LightCondensed /GaramondITCbyBT-LightCondItalic /GaramondITCbyBT-LightItalic /GaramondITCbyBT-LightNarrow /GaramondITCbyBT-LightNarrowItal /GaramondITCbyBT-Ultra /GaramondITCbyBT-UltraCondensed /GaramondITCbyBT-UltraCondItalic /GaramondITCbyBT-UltraItalic /Garamond-Kursiv /Garamond-KursivHalbfett /Garamond-LightCondensed /Garamond-LightCondensedItalic /GaramondThree /GaramondThree-Bold /GaramondThree-BoldItalic /GaramondThree-Italic /GaramondThreeSMSspl /GaramondThreespl /GaramondThreeSpl-Bold /GaramondThreeSpl-Italic /GarthGraphic /GarthGraphic-Black /GarthGraphic-Bold /GarthGraphic-BoldCondensed /GarthGraphic-BoldItalic /GarthGraphic-Condensed /GarthGraphic-ExtraBold /GarthGraphic-Italic /Geometric231BT-HeavyC /GeometricSlab712BT-BoldA /GeometricSlab712BT-ExtraBoldA /GeometricSlab712BT-LightA /GeometricSlab712BT-LightItalicA /GeometricSlab712BT-MediumA /GeometricSlab712BT-MediumItalA /Giddyup /Giddyup-Thangs /GillSans /GillSans-Bold /GillSans-BoldCondensed /GillSans-BoldItalic /GillSans-Condensed /GillSans-ExtraBold /GillSans-Italic /GillSans-Light /GillSans-LightItalic /GillSans-UltraBold /GillSans-UltraBoldCondensed /Gill-Special /Giovanni-Bold /Giovanni-BoldItalic /Giovanni-Book /Giovanni-BookItalic /Glypha /Glypha-Bold /Glypha-BoldOblique /Glypha-Oblique /Goudy /Goudy-Bold /Goudy-BoldItalic /Goudy-ExtraBold /Goudy-Italic /GoudyOldStyleBT-Bold /GoudyOldStyleBT-BoldItalic /GoudyOldStyleBT-ExtraBold /GoudyOldStyleBT-Italic /GoudyOldStyleBT-Roman /GoudySans-Bold /GoudySans-BoldItalic /GoudySansITCbyBT-Bold /GoudySansITCbyBT-BoldItalic /GoudySansITCbyBT-Medium /GoudySansITCbyBT-MediumItalic /GoudySans-Medium /GoudySans-MediumItalic /Granjon /Granjon-Bold /Granjon-BoldOsF /Granjon-Italic /Granjon-ItalicOsF /Granjon-SC /GreymantleMVB-Ornaments /Helvetica /Helvetica-Black /Helvetica-BlackOblique /Helvetica-Black-SemiBold /Helvetica-Bold /Helvetica-BoldOblique /Helvetica-Condensed /Helvetica-Condensed-Black /Helvetica-Condensed-BlackObl /Helvetica-Condensed-Bold /Helvetica-Condensed-BoldObl /Helvetica-Condensed-Light /Helvetica-Condensed-LightObl /Helvetica-Condensed-Oblique /Helvetica-Light /Helvetica-LightOblique /Helvetica-Narrow /Helvetica-Narrow-Bold /Helvetica-Narrow-BoldOblique /Helvetica-Narrow-Oblique /HelveticaNeue-BlackCond /HelveticaNeue-BlackCondObl /HelveticaNeue-Bold /HelveticaNeue-BoldCond /HelveticaNeue-BoldCondObl /HelveticaNeue-BoldExt /HelveticaNeue-BoldExtObl /HelveticaNeue-BoldItalic /HelveticaNeue-Condensed /HelveticaNeue-CondensedObl /HelveticaNeue-ExtBlackCond /HelveticaNeue-ExtBlackCondObl /HelveticaNeue-Extended /HelveticaNeue-ExtendedObl /HelveticaNeue-Heavy /HelveticaNeue-HeavyCond /HelveticaNeue-HeavyCondObl /HelveticaNeue-HeavyExt /HelveticaNeue-HeavyExtObl /HelveticaNeue-HeavyItalic /HelveticaNeue-Italic /HelveticaNeue-Light /HelveticaNeue-LightCond /HelveticaNeue-LightCondObl /HelveticaNeue-LightItalic /HelveticaNeueLTStd-Md /HelveticaNeueLTStd-MdIt /HelveticaNeue-Medium /HelveticaNeue-MediumCond /HelveticaNeue-MediumCondObl /HelveticaNeue-MediumExt /HelveticaNeue-MediumExtObl /HelveticaNeue-MediumItalic /HelveticaNeue-Roman /HelveticaNeue-ThinCond /HelveticaNeue-ThinCondObl /HelveticaNeue-UltraLigCond /HelveticaNeue-UltraLigCondObl /Helvetica-Oblique /HelvLight /Humanist521BT-Bold /Humanist521BT-BoldCondensed /Humanist521BT-BoldItalic /Humanist521BT-ExtraBold /Humanist521BT-Italic /Humanist521BT-Light /Humanist521BT-LightItalic /Humanist521BT-Roman /Humanist521BT-RomanCondensed /Humanist521BT-UltraBold /Humanist521BT-XtraBoldCondensed /Humanist777BT-BlackB /Humanist777BT-BlackItalicB /Humanist777BT-BoldB /Humanist777BT-BoldItalicB /Humanist777BT-ItalicB /Humanist777BT-LightB /Humanist777BT-LightItalicB /Humanist777BT-RomanB /ICMEX10 /ICMMI8 /ICMSY8 /ICMTT8 /ILASY8 /ILCMSS8 /ILCMSSB8 /ILCMSSI8 /Imago-Book /Imago-BookItalic /Imago-ExtraBold /Imago-ExtraBoldItalic /Imago-Medium /Imago-MediumItalic /Industria-Inline /Industria-InlineA /Industria-Solid /Industria-SolidA /Insignia /Insignia-A /IPAExtras /IPAHighLow /IPAKiel /IPAKielSeven /IPAsans /JoannaMT /JoannaMT-Bold /JoannaMT-BoldItalic /JoannaMT-Italic /KlangMT /Kuenstler480BT-Black /Kuenstler480BT-Bold /Kuenstler480BT-BoldItalic /Kuenstler480BT-Italic /Kuenstler480BT-Roman /KunstlerschreibschD-Bold /KunstlerschreibschD-Medi /Lapidary333BT-Black /Lapidary333BT-Bold /Lapidary333BT-BoldItalic /Lapidary333BT-Italic /Lapidary333BT-Roman /LASY10 /LASY5 /LASY6 /LASY7 /LASY8 /LASY9 /LASYB10 /LatinMT-Condensed /LCIRCLE10 /LCIRCLEW10 /LCMSS8 /LCMSSB8 /LCMSSI8 /LDecorationPi-One /LDecorationPi-Two /Leawood-Black /Leawood-BlackItalic /Leawood-Bold /Leawood-BoldItalic /Leawood-Book /Leawood-BookItalic /Leawood-Medium /Leawood-MediumItalic /LegacySans-Bold /LegacySans-BoldItalic /LegacySans-Book /LegacySans-BookItalic /LegacySans-Medium /LegacySans-MediumItalic /LegacySans-Ultra /LegacySerif-Bold /LegacySerif-BoldItalic /LegacySerif-Book /LegacySerif-BookItalic /LegacySerif-Medium /LegacySerif-MediumItalic /LegacySerif-Ultra /LetterGothic /LetterGothic-Bold /LetterGothic-BoldSlanted /LetterGothic-Slanted /Life-Bold /Life-Italic /Life-Roman /LINE10 /LINEW10 /Lithos-Black /Lithos-Regular /LOGO10 /LOGO8 /LOGO9 /LOGOBF10 /LOGOSL10 /LOMD-Normal /LubalinGraph-Book /LubalinGraph-BookOblique /LubalinGraph-Demi /LubalinGraph-DemiOblique /LucidaMath-Symbol /LydianBT-Bold /LydianBT-BoldItalic /LydianBT-Italic /LydianBT-Roman /LydianCursiveBT-Regular /Marigold /MathematicalPi-Five /MathematicalPi-Four /MathematicalPi-One /MathematicalPi-Six /MathematicalPi-Three /MathematicalPi-Two /Melior /Melior-Bold /Melior-BoldItalic /Melior-Italic /MercuriusCT-Black /MercuriusCT-BlackItalic /MercuriusCT-Light /MercuriusCT-LightItalic /MercuriusCT-Medium /MercuriusCT-MediumItalic /MercuriusMT-BoldScript /Meridien-Medium /Meridien-MediumItalic /Meridien-Roman /Minion-Black /Minion-Bold /Minion-BoldCondensed /Minion-BoldCondensedItalic /Minion-BoldItalic /Minion-Condensed /Minion-CondensedItalic /MinionExp-Italic /MinionExp-Semibold /MinionExp-SemiboldItalic /Minion-Italic /Minion-Ornaments /Minion-Regular /Minion-Semibold /Minion-SemiboldItalic /MonaLisa-Recut /MSAM10 /MSAM10A /MSAM5 /MSAM6 /MSAM7 /MSAM8 /MSAM9 /MSBM10 /MSBM10A /MSBM5 /MSBM6 /MSBM7 /MSBM8 /MSBM9 /MTEX /MTEXB /MTEXH /MTGU /MTGUB /MTMI /MTMIB /MTMIH /MTMS /MTMSB /MTMUB /MTMUH /MTSY /MTSYB /MTSYH /MTSYN /MusicalSymbols-Normal /Myriad-Bold /Myriad-BoldItalic /Myriad-CnBold /Myriad-CnBoldItalic /Myriad-CnItalic /Myriad-CnSemibold /Myriad-CnSemiboldItalic /Myriad-Condensed /Myriad-Italic /Myriad-Roman /Myriad-Sketch /Myriad-Tilt /NeuzeitS-Book ] /NeverEmbed [ true ] /AntiAliasColorImages false /CropColorImages true /ColorImageMinResolution 150 /ColorImageMinResolutionPolicy /OK /DownsampleColorImages true /ColorImageDownsampleType /Bicubic /ColorImageResolution 300 /ColorImageDepth -1 /ColorImageMinDownsampleDepth 1 /ColorImageDownsampleThreshold 1.50000 /EncodeColorImages true /ColorImageFilter /DCTEncode /AutoFilterColorImages true /ColorImageAutoFilterStrategy /JPEG /ColorACSImageDict << /QFactor 0.15 /HSamples [1 1 1 1] /VSamples [1 1 1 1] >> /ColorImageDict << /QFactor 0.15 /HSamples [1 1 1 1] /VSamples [1 1 1 1] >> /JPEG2000ColorACSImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 30 >> /JPEG2000ColorImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 30 >> /AntiAliasGrayImages false /CropGrayImages true /GrayImageMinResolution 150 /GrayImageMinResolutionPolicy /OK /DownsampleGrayImages true /GrayImageDownsampleType /Bicubic /GrayImageResolution 300 /GrayImageDepth -1 /GrayImageMinDownsampleDepth 2 /GrayImageDownsampleThreshold 1.50000 /EncodeGrayImages true /GrayImageFilter /DCTEncode /AutoFilterGrayImages true /GrayImageAutoFilterStrategy /JPEG /GrayACSImageDict << /QFactor 0.15 /HSamples [1 1 1 1] /VSamples [1 1 1 1] >> /GrayImageDict << /QFactor 0.15 /HSamples [1 1 1 1] /VSamples [1 1 1 1] >> /JPEG2000GrayACSImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 30 >> /JPEG2000GrayImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 30 >> /AntiAliasMonoImages false /CropMonoImages true /MonoImageMinResolution 1200 /MonoImageMinResolutionPolicy /OK /DownsampleMonoImages true /MonoImageDownsampleType /Bicubic /MonoImageResolution 1200 /MonoImageDepth -1 /MonoImageDownsampleThreshold 1.50000 /EncodeMonoImages true /MonoImageFilter /CCITTFaxEncode /MonoImageDict << /K -1 >> /AllowPSXObjects false /CheckCompliance [ /None ] /PDFX1aCheck false /PDFX3Check false /PDFXCompliantPDFOnly false /PDFXNoTrimBoxError true /PDFXTrimBoxToMediaBoxOffset [ 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 ] /PDFXSetBleedBoxToMediaBox false /PDFXBleedBoxToTrimBoxOffset [ 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 ] /PDFXOutputIntentProfile (U.S. Web Coated \050SWOP\051 v2) /PDFXOutputConditionIdentifier () /PDFXOutputCondition () /PDFXRegistryName (http://www.color.org) /PDFXTrapped /Unknown /CreateJDFFile false /SyntheticBoldness 1.000000 /Description << /FRA /JPN /DEU /PTB /DAN /NLD /ESP /SUO /ITA /NOR /SVE /ENU >> >> setdistillerparams << /HWResolution [2400 2400] /PageSize [612.000 792.000] >> setpagedevice work_bh2srh2ffvdh7e62p3dsutan6q ---- Efficiency of Justice and Economic Systems Procedia Economics and Finance 17 ( 2014 ) 104 – 112 2212-5671 © 2014 The Authors. Published by Elsevier B.V. This is an open access article under the CC BY-NC-ND license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/). Selection and peer-review under responsibility of the Organizing Committee of IES 2013. doi: 10.1016/S2212-5671(14)00884-3 ScienceDirect Available online at www.sciencedirect.com Innovation and Society 2013 Conference, IES 2013 Efficiency of Justice and Economic Systems Marilene Lorizioa*, Antonia Rosa Gurrieria a Department of Law, University of Foggia, Largo Papa Giovanni Paolo II, 71100 Foggia, Italy Abstract The growth of an economy depends not only on economic factors, but also on institutions, the citizens' trust in them, by the sharing of values and expectations. The differences between public policies and institutions are often regarded as one of the key explanations of the wide differences in levels and growth rates of per capita across countries. Among the institutions that have the greatest impact on economic performance, the legal and judicial system plays a prominent role. Understanding how laws and regulations affect economic behaviour is fundamental in modern economies and the economy facilitates the identification of those that are, in each country system, the incentives to the litigation, the process of litigation itself and the costs, in order to verify the distributive impact of the different legal and judicial systems and what features they should have to encourage economic growth. The operation of a legal system may impact on many dimensions of development: equity, the optimal allocation of resources, and the increase in total factor productivity. Moreover, the role of the judicial system in determining its dysfunctions can affect economic growth. In fact, Italian economic growth has been and is definitely hampered by the length a s well as by the civil and criminal justice processes, which reduces legal certainty and confidence, increases the risk of economic activities and therefore reduces the propensity to invest. The Italian judicial system has many efficiency and organization problems, resulting in a lack of its credibility. These are very intricate, and are the product of a mixture of features that are very difficult to isolate. The aim of this work is to assess the ways in which the administration of justice in Italy influences the choices and behaviours of the two main economic actors - households and businesses - analysing if there is any (a) symmetry in their preferences. In fact, there are many factors that determine the failure of Italian justice, and among these also the users of the justice services produce a collapse in justice system when they take legal actions only for postponing a payment or avoiding an obligation. Thus, the source of the problem and its resolution could be identified in the distorted incentives generated by all of the rules connected with the process. © 2014 The Authors. Published by Elsevier B.V. Selection and peer-review under responsibility of the Organizing Committee of IES 2013. Keywords: K00- general; K410-litigation process a* Corresponding author. Tel.: +39-0881-582246; fax: +39-0881-582215. E-mail address: marilene.lorizio@unifg.it © 2014 The Authors. Published by Elsevier B.V. This is an open access article under the CC BY-NC-ND license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/). Selection and peer-review under responsibility of the Organizing Committee of IES 2013. http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1016/S2212-5671(14)00884-3&domain=pdf 105 Marilene Lorizio and Antonia Rosa Gurrieri / Procedia Economics and Finance 17 ( 2014 ) 104 – 112 Economic growth depends on economic factors, institutions and the level of trust citizens have in institutional powers. The differences between public policies and institutions can also explain the differences in per-capita growth level between Countries. Scully (1988) demonstrates that countries with a good level of institutions, in terms of stability and per capita measurement, grow faster than those with a low level of institutions. Economic performances are influenced by the legal and judicial system, capable of forming the rules of the game. Every society is governed by a set of rules that operate within a framework of formal legal institutions - tangible structures and codified norms - and informal ones, such as customs, habits, informal rules, moral codes, routine etc. Understanding how laws and regulations affect economic behaviour (choices) is fundamental in modern economies. Moreover, an economy facilitates the identification of those aspects that are, in each country system, the incentives to litigation, the process of litigation itself and the costs, in order to verify the distributive impact of the different legal and judicial systems and what features they should have in order to encourage economic growth. The importance of the rules and their relevance for the economic growth is also widely acknowledged in academic and institutional framework, and the role of judicial systems in determining economic performance has achieved ever more consideration in recent years. This is demonstrated by the research of many international organizations (World Bank, IMF). Numerous empirical analysis generally agree that quantitative and statistically significant effects of the "quality" of the right are the main indicators of economic performance of a country. Indeed, a legal system can affect different dimensions of the development process. These are equity, the optimal allocation of resources, and the increase in total factor productivity. In addition, some aspects of the legal system may influence the behaviour and choices of economic actors, determining the accumulation of physical and human capital (decisions relating to investment and training). Thus, the role of the judicial system in determining its dysfunctions can affect economic growth. It is hard to identify a structure of indicators of the quality and efficiency of justice. In this direction, the Cepej report highlights mainly the problem of the length of the processes. In fact, the excessive length of civil proceedings does not guarantee adequate protection of many contracts. Actually, Italian economic growth has been, and still is, definitely hampered - by purely economic intrinsic factors, - by the length of the civil and criminal justice processes, as well as by the processes themselves, which reduces legal certainty and confidence, increases the risk of economic activities and therefore reduces the propensity to invest. The quality of a judicial system can be estimated in numerous expressions: the length and the quality of the judgments, the efficient use of public resources, and the opportunity of access to justice for all citizens. Among the reasons of impediments of justice, the literature indicates the level of formality of procedures (Djankov et al., 2003), organizational structures, the method of work within the judicial offices (Zan, 2006) and the incentives of the parties engaged in service provision, especially judges and lawyers (Marchesi, 2003; Buscaglia and Dakolias, 1999). In literature, institutional interaction (new institutional economics) starts with Williamson (1975; 2000) who believes that transaction is only a bilateral relation. Only later does he connect transaction cost theory with relational contracts and fundamental transformation. After 1980, neoclassical theory moves from the monopolistic paradigm in favour of the liberalization of public utilities. At this stage we can assist in the development of the relations between public sector activities and private ones. Unfortunately, the binomial public-private relationship does not produce the expected results. The reintroduction (Menrad, 2004; North, 2005) of new institutional economics reveals that institutions are able to explain economic transformations and performances through a comparative analysis. The active actors in this process are entrepreneurs, employees and others, excluding the legislative figures. Personal maximization and limited rationality are at the base of the movement and institutional and contractual coordination are the mechanisms of the process. Thus, it is rather difficult to identify the factors that help justice to operate efficiently. In fact, the main problem is the lack of market benchmarks, which are able to determine the right-price of the services offered and the factors used. It is also difficult to identify good indicators of performance for the Justice Sector. In fact, the same factors are always considered both for performance indicators or inputs sector productivity. Thus, efficiency coincides with productivity, however this is not always true and is potentially dangerous. Certainly productivity and efficiency are interrelated, because both are related to the resources available to the sector, but at the same time they present very different characteristics. 106 Marilene Lorizio and Antonia Rosa Gurrieri / Procedia Economics and Finance 17 ( 2014 ) 104 – 112 However, the main problem concerns the criteria needed to measure them. An indicator of productivity could be the distribution of the resources of justice; a possible indicator of this is given by the percentage of positions for magistrates left vacant by district. An additional indicator may be the number of cases allotted per magistrate and the distribution of the judiciary resources for the persecution of various crimes. Currently, the allocation of resources in the sector is through rationing and queues, which are patently inefficient criteria. In general, allocation processes that do not use the price system are neither transparent nor efficient. Therefore, economic efficiency is the ability of the courts to make fair, predictable and timely decisions. All these attributes act as an incentive for investment, growth and technological progress. Shleifer and Vishny (1997) argue that the quality/efficiency of a judicial system could be estimated on the frequency with which people resort to it, instead of evaluating the alternative mechanisms for conflict resolution. In practice, the frequency of litigation is an indicator to the proper functioning - or not - of the justice sector and, indirectly, to its impact on the choices of economic agents. Many studies have shown that the inefficiency of justice in the South of Italy is produced by the supply side, and is detectable in a disproportionate number of judges rather than in the amount of processes that they are capable of defining. On the other hand, in the rest of the country, inefficiency is mainly influenced by the importance of the load of criminal cases that have not been disposed of in prior periods. We take the view that, in the south especially, the demand for justice coming from the territory exerts a considerable influence on the in/efficiency of justice; it is measured by the number of cases registered, and tied to the rate of litigation, so the inefficiency of Southern justice also takes place on the demand side and has a high social weighting. So, the operation of the civil justice system is negatively affected by high litigation, concentrated in certain subjects and geographical areas. Moreover, the multi-dimensionality of good-justice is underlined by the fact that it takes on the role of both the output of its production function - it is our intention to try to build on this in subsequent studies – and that of the input in the economic model that seeks to measure the social capital of a nation. Many studies on social capital show how an imperfect justice system translated into an (distorted) incentive can lead to irregular/illegal behaviours, slowing the formation of networks of mutual trust. Therefore the existence of negative reciprocal externalities between slow justice and inefficient economic system is hypothesized. The hypothesis is that the slow pace of justice will damage the efficiency of the economic system because it reduces the opportunities for the protection of the injured party, who sees the increase of the opportunity cost related to the expectation of the end of the process. At the same time, the guilty party instead sees an increase in the likelihood of a favourable transaction or even the relinquishment of protection by the same plaintiff. The duration of the process also provides useful information on the system of penalties in force, that impacts also on the accumulation of social capital. If the demand for justice is artificially expanded, the resulted uncertainty of protection implies partially hidden charges, but which are costly to the community. Therefore, the inefficiency of the civil justice translates into uncertainty, which is a powerful factor of friction in the functioning of an economy, as well as injustice. When this uncertainty produced by the inefficiency of justice is combined with a growing distrust in justice itself, it turns into a consistent friction factor in the functioning of the economy. In this respect, the Bank of Italy shows that the annual loss in gross national product attributable to the defects of our civil justice may come to a percentage point. In Italy, in fact, the slow pace of justice involves both social costs-i.e. a poor service to the community – and economic costs compared to the need for legal certainty of the economic system as a whole. These serious diseconomies are aggravated by direct costs to the public budget, because the State is obliged to ensure equitable relief in favour of those who have had to endure the unreasonable length of time for civil or criminal process. It has been also highlighted that its slow pace of justice represents one of the main constraints to foreign investment in Italy. In addition, the slow pace of justice accentuates regional disparities. In fact, in regions where there is a higher number of pending cases, the bank interest rates are higher, because of the connected uncertainty, thus determining difficulties in accessing credit. The credit crunch in turn leads to a contraction of private investments, a reduced economic growth and an increase in unemployment and crime. These elements do not create a favourable climate or a regulatory framework conducive to business activity. Therefore, the performances of the judicial system affect the results of commercial litigation, the certainty of property rights, the quality of legislation, and the development of criminal activities. In addition, an inefficient justice system leads to an increase in transaction costs related to the lack of mechanisms that ensure compliance with the legal rights and obligations. Finally, there was also a dearth of reliable information about the credibility and 107 Marilene Lorizio and Antonia Rosa Gurrieri / Procedia Economics and Finance 17 ( 2014 ) 104 – 112 reputation of the justice system of the country, or at least distorted information, incomplete and focused mainly on the problems of the sector, which certainly acts as a deterrent to decisions of investment by both domestic and foreign operators, producing negative effects on economic growth processes. Consequently, dysfunctional judicial systems may discourage saving, and increase capital flight, decreasing the amount of funds available to finance investment. Instead, well-functioning judicial systems promote growth and encourage a more rapid accumulation of factors of production. Above all, investment in both physical and human capital will be supported by secure property rights, well-functioning legal and judicial systems and political stability (Schmidt-Hebbel et al, 1996 and Alesina and Perotti 1994). Among all the institutions, the market most requires a reliable justice, well functioning. This is necessary because the market consists of a set of relationships, agreements, and connections among people, which are based on trust. In fact, the existence of a healthy justice system activates a process of self-respect that in turn feeds a greater efficiency; the reputation so conquered represents a further incentive to the respect of the contracts, thereby reducing a further distorting element of efficiency, given by the presence of incentives to opportunism. Generally speaking, the reduced competitiveness of our firms is due to fragility of our production system that makes it weak in front of the new competitive environment. These deficiencies depend on internal factors of a firm - such as the small size and limitations connected with familial management models - and on external factors. Such devices include a complex and uncertain regulatory framework, the excessive length of judicial procedures, the weight of bureaucracy and the inadequacy of a protection contracts’ system. A justice clogged and slowed down leads the economic system and firms to behave in an economically inefficient way, because the choices are intended to minimize the uncertainty represented by a process. The consequence is a reduction in competitiveness. The choices of firms pursue not only the criteria of economic efficiency, but they aim to avoid the consequences of a malfunction of the justice system (distortion of incentives). In this way the inefficiency of justice results in inefficiency in the choices of economic agents. In Italy, disincentives arising from the failure of justice in the economic system are numerous: contraction of start-ups (discouragement effect); the preference for the small size, which erodes the competitiveness of the national production system (dimensional effect); the tendency to the "loyalty of partnership" in trade relations (inefficiency in seizing the opportunities offered by a competitive system); frequent recourse to forms or business combinations in which the contract will be fulfilled by forms of punishment other than civil justice, such as reputation, sharing suppliers/information technologies, belonging to the same chain (management inefficiency); tendency of firms to integrate vertically and a system translate into an additional cost to the country's economy, which is identified in lower investment, the phenomena of freezing of capital, excessive use of the banking system. Summarizing, because contract and property rights are not appropriately enforced, firms may decide to not pursue a number of activities, to relinquish the opportunity to specialize and exploit economies of scale, to combine inputs inefficiently, not to allocate production in the most efficient way, keep resources unemployed etc. The selected period is 2003-2011. This choice is due both to the complete information about the involved variables, and to the idea to evaluate the crisis effects. In this stage we consider only two effects of justice’s length: discouragement effect and dimensional effect. In this section we use also the industrial dimensional class 20-49 because, analysing data, we notice some peculiarities in the dimensional dynamic of this category. For describing this phenomenon we compare the fixed base index numbers - with percentage base, of the following variables. Actually we are still studying this phenomenon, but in this work we offer some ideas about it. 108 Marilene Lorizio and Antonia Rosa Gurrieri / Procedia Economics and Finance 17 ( 2014 ) 104 – 112 Source: own elaborations on ISTAT, Justice Department and Bank of Italy Fig. 1: Trend among CPL, TF and F1 (observed and indexed data) 109 Marilene Lorizio and Antonia Rosa Gurrieri / Procedia Economics and Finance 17 ( 2014 ) 104 – 112 Source: own elaborations on ISTAT data Fig. 2: New procedures, Total number of firms and Firms 20-49 (observed and indexed data) 110 Marilene Lorizio and Antonia Rosa Gurrieri / Procedia Economics and Finance 17 ( 2014 ) 104 – 112 In figure 1 we observe the relation between civil processes’ length (CPL- average days, Bianco et al., 2007) and the total number of industrial firms (TF – number and indexed number) and the industrial dimensional class 20-49 (F1- number and indexed number). The variable CPL is growing with some exceptions connected with some reforms in civil justice. Both the other variables, TF and F1, are in line, and they register a very limited increasing for the period, the only exception is a small decrease in 2011, probably connected to the crisis. In figure 2 we evaluate, for the selected period, the trend among the new legal actions (LLA - indexed number), as an indicator of the length of justice, and TF and F1. Obviously, both TF and F1 present the same trend of figure 1. The variable LLA presents a trend quite in line with CPL. We explain this peculiarity because the less LLA, the higher speed in closing the existing proceedings. This work is a primary study of a wider project that analyses a wider range of variables in order to demonstrate the effects of an inefficient judicial system on an economic productive system. We are still collecting data from different sources. We know that there is a lack of good statistical information but we hope to statistically supporting our idea using more and interesting variables. The selected variables were ready-references. We calculated Pearson and Spearman coefficients, but the results were not totally significant. Therefore, we prefer only to describe the meaning of the work using few variables. With respect to the size of a firm, there are many ways in which the inefficiency of justice can affect the dimension of the business. Generally the performance of the judicial system may influence several features of firms’ performance like employment, investment, organizational paradigm, and contractual relationships with counterparts, all of which have an effect on firm size. According to the literature, an inefficient justice implies a smaller average size of firms. Kumar, Rajan and Zingales (1999), point out that in Western European countries, superior judicial systems are connected with significant average firm size. Moreover, Beck, Demirg-Kunt and Maksimovic (2006) analysing the largest industrial firms in 44 countries, demonstrate that firm size is positively related with institutional progress. The size of Italian firms is on average 40 % smaller than other European countries. The undersized firms are considered a disadvantage of the Italian productive system and the main source of the Italian low productivity and GDP growth. Furthermore, justice efficiency in Italy is very weak, according to the World Bank’s Doing Business report. This inefficiency is largely associated to the excessive length of judicial proceedings. Indeed, the excessive length of judicial proceedings decreases contract enforcement. Above all, an inefficient judicial system has an effect on investment choices by firms and in this way it influences firm size. In fact, imperfect contract enforcement amplifies the risks associated to the contracts and this can result in less investment and less growth occasions. Moreover, the performance of justice can determine the employment decisions of firms through its effects on the enforcement of employment legislation. In addition, to avoid the high transaction costs related to reduced enforceability of contracts, firms tend to vertically integrate. Finally, in response to the poor enforceability of contracts, firms are less disposed to interact with new partners and tend to intensify reliance on relational contracts. These relational contracts usually produce barriers to entry for new firms that are commonly smaller than incumbent ones, thus decreasing average firm size (Johnson et al., 2002). So, domestic enterprises need to avoid the uncertainties, the costs and times associated with any litigation, and therefore perform economically inefficient choices. Business decisions involve a reduced demand for justice, while non-entrepreneurs perform opposite choices. There is a sort of gap in the demand for justice by families (characterized by high litigation, resulting in the crowding of the courts) and companies (which have avoiding lawsuits among their primary objectives). Therefore, the uncertainty acts as an incentive on the two types of users (individuals and firms) in the opposite way: in fact, while it represents an unknown cost that it is best to avoid as much as possible for businesses, it is an input to opportunistic behaviour on the part of private enterprises, who rely on a long and not foreseeable time that characterizes its administration in order to postpone their contractual obligations. At the base of the choices, there is a common factor represented by the distrust of the proper administration of justice. In Italy, a considerable portion of the demand of justice is pathological because there is no request to the courts to resolve legal and uncertain difficulties, but to obtain economic advantages by exploiting the inefficiency of the system. Among the reasons that support this type of demand and determine incentives to engage in a process rather than executing own obligations, we have a positive differential between the market interest rate and the legal rate of 111 Marilene Lorizio and Antonia Rosa Gurrieri / Procedia Economics and Finance 17 ( 2014 ) 104 – 112 interest. Moreover, the legal rules for distributing the costs of the proceedings are not adequately penalizing for the loser person. The numerous recourses to the courts seem originated from a phenomenon known in literature as moral hazard: people are pushed to engage in hazardous activities when there is a high chance that the costs associated with a negative outcome from falling on society. Our attention has focused also on two interrelated aspects: i. the ways in which an inefficient justice system affects the functioning of the credit system and the relative cost (interest rate), as well as the effects that the increase in these costs exerts on the amount of domestic investment, thereby undermining the potential growth of the country; ii. the ways in which an ineffective justice system is a deterrent to foreign investment, thus compromising the territorial competitiveness of the country. A series of panel surveys on the functioning of justice in the Italian provinces (Felli et al, 2007), shows that credit is more rationed in Italian provinces with more ongoing or pending processes. This result is witnessed by some international studies that insert between the proxies of justice inefficiency, the amplitude of mortgage markets. The effect associated with this restriction is given by the increase in interest rates, and its result is widespread in geographic areas characterized by a slower justice, since the level of interest rates are also the result of competition among lenders. The interest rates are charged by the credit system incorporating "slow" justice and when the costs associated with legal proceedings necessary to enforce receivables grow, the conditions applied to mortgages are heavier. In fact, in decisions relating to the different loan conditions, banks seem to consider the probable costs to be faced in the event that the subsidized subject is in default. This widespread tendency produces a crowding out of private investments and the multiplier associated effects. This result is even more critical in a globalized context, where companies are multinational and tend to break away from the territory of reference and lose the direct connection with a specific ordering of the State. It implies the occurrence in time of opportunity to “choice” law. In this way, states are obliged to confront and compete also in economic terms, with respect to which, reference is made to the judgment delivered by the rating agencies on a range of economic/financial parameters, even in legal terms. The perception of market participants on the functionality of public administration, the effectiveness of legal instruments, and the timeliness of administrative and judicial decisions are of strategic importance. At present the benchmarks related to this competitive process between jurisdictions does not appear in our favour. The costs and timing of our justice system are high and uncertain, and the consequences are spread throughout the country. A further disincentive to foreign investment would seem to lie in the lack of political credibility of a country, as perceived by both the private sector and externals, as already documented in some reports of the World Bank (it is revealed that the countries with a high perception of credibility have high levels of investment and vice versa). Therefore, legal uncertainty − linked to the problems of efficiency of the justice system− and institutional uncertainty − linked to the credibility of national policies − end up making unstable rules of the game. Greater efficiency in the administration of justice can be obtained primarily by solving the problem in the stock of arrears to be disposed of. To this end, the actions to be taken should include measures of deflation procedures, adjustment of the workforce, and redefinition of the areas of territorial jurisdiction. Institutional reform also seems necessary, especially in civil trials, which eliminates the strong incentives that force stakeholders today into behaviours that induce the lengthening of the process. A way to discourage individuals from appeals to justice should be identified, even for less relevant cases, which aggravate the cost and promote further alternative forms of administration of justice. Perhaps the relative deterrence should be practiced also against lawyers who sponsor these types of disputes. In the light of the current economic crisis, the even higher costs - monetary, social and economic - referring to the justice sector and associated with a significant inefficiency of the same, make the need for reform ever more stringent in order to aim at making t he justice system efficient, rapid, reliable and accessible to all. Moreover, as in public services sectors, management also focuses on the standardization of certain production processes (ratings/processes/ discussions/hearings), ensuring the same quality of related services. In general, the three conditions necessary for a more efficient management of all public services - including justice - are represented by the measurement of performance, transparency and meritocracy. This involves adopting a particular perspective of the concept of “justice services” and accepts the hypothesis to estimate its comparative costs at the local level (benchmark). The delays and inefficiencies that characterize the justice system have been transformed from a right recognized, protected and 112 Marilene Lorizio and Antonia Rosa Gurrieri / Procedia Economics and Finance 17 ( 2014 ) 104 – 112 guaranteed to all citizens to an object of consumption of the same, for which the rates of litigation seem to grow in proportion to the time of justice. This circumstance has transformed the citizen from justice user to consumer of justice, aggravating the possibilities of governance of the system. Generally, legal reforms are not produced exogenously, expressing the interest of some groups in society. Therefore, it is necessary to identify which are the conditions that lead a country to carry out legal reform. These vary according to the composition of a society, the distribution of income and the need to protect the property rights. The justice reform must first restore to the sector its dignity as a public provision constitutionally protected and, above all, at the service of all citizens, defined as users and not as consumers of a good that cannot be traded on markets. Finally, any reform must be the result of a legal, healthy culture and of responsible ethics. The future sector will be self-critical, suitable to adapt and experiment (i.e. not resistant to change), prepared to proceed from a system designed to satisfy the producers of justice to one intended to benefit its users and thus act as a driving force for the economic progress, ethical and social development of the country. References Alesina, A., Perotti, R., 1994. The political economy of growth: a critical survey of the recent literature. The World Bank Economic Review, vol. 8, no. 3. Beck, T., Demirguc-Kunt, A., Maksimovic, V., 2006. The influence of financial and legal institutions on firm size, Journal of Banking & Finance, Elsevier, vol. 30(11), pages 2995-3015, November. Bianco, M., Giacomelli, S., Giorgiantonio, C., Palumbo, G, Szego, B., 2007. La durata (eccessiva) dei procedimenti civili in Italia: offerta, domanda o rito? Rivista di Politica Economica, vol. 97, serie III, fascicolo IX-X.). Buscaglia, E, Dakolias, M., 1999. Comparative International Study of Court Performance Indicators. The World Bank, Legal Department. Djankov, S., La Porta, R., Lopez de Silanes, F. e Shleifer, A., 2003. Courts, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 453-517. Felli, L., Tria, G., Londono-Bedoya, D., Solferino, N., 2007. The “Demand for Justice” in Italy: Civil Litigation and the Judicial System. In: Padovano F., Ricciuti R. (eds.), Italian Institutional Reforms. A Public Choice Perspective. New York: Springer, pp. 155-177. Johnson S., McMillan J., Woodruff C., 2002, Courts and Relational Contracts, Journalof Law, Economics and Organization, n. 1. Kumar, K., Rajan, R., Zingales, L., 1999. What Determines Firm Size, NBER, WorkingPaper, n. 7208. Marchesi, D., 2003. Litiganti, avvocati e magistrati: Diritto ed economia del processo civile. Il Mulino. Menard, C., 2004. The Economics of Hybrid Organizations. Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 160, 345-370 North, D.C., 2005. Institutions and the Performance over Time, Dordrecht, Springer. Schmidt-Hebbel, K., Servén, L., Solimano, A., 1996. Saving and investment: paradigms, puzzles, policies. The World Bank Research Observer, vol. 11, no. 1. Scully, G. W., 1988. The institutional framework and economic development. Journal of Political Economy 96, no. 3. Shleifer, A,. Vishny, R.W., 1997. A Survey of Corporate Governance. The Journal of Finance 52, 2, 737-783. Williamson, O., 1975. Market and Hierarchies. Analysis and Antitrust Implications. New York , Free Press. Williamson, O. E., 2000. The New Institutional Economics: Taking Stock, Looking Ahead. Journal of Economic Literature 38, 595-613. Zan, S., 2006. Il sistema organizzativo della giustizia civile in Italia: caratteristiche e prospettive, Quaderni di giustizia e organizzazione, n. 1. work_bhne6equxnbdjirsg7lbkugzoa ---- © Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, 2013 DOI 10.1163/17455243-4681035 Journal of Moral Philosophy (2013) DOI 10.1163/17455243-4681035 brill.com/jmp JOURNAL OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY When Justice Demands Inequality John Thrasher* Department of Philosophy, University of Arizona jthrashe@email.arizona.edu Keith Hankins** Department of Philosophy, University of Arizona Department of Economics, Rutgers University Hankins@email.arizona.edu Abstract In Rescuing Justice and Equality G.A. Cohen argues that justice requires an uncompromising commitment to equality. Cohen also argues, however, that justice must be sensitive to other values, including a robust commitment to individual freedom and to the welfare of the community. We ask whether a commitment to these other values means that, despite Cohen’s commitment to equality, his view requires that we make room for inequality in the name of justice? We argue that even on Cohen’s version of egalitarianism equality, freedom, and welfare are not always compatible. Justice will require trade-offs between these values. Sometimes, equality will need to be sacrificed. This is a surprising result and to show it, we use two informal impossibility proofs drawn from examples in Rescuing Justice and Equality. Keywords G.A. Cohen; Egalitarianism; Impossibility Proof; John Rawls; Amartya Sen In Rescuing Justice and Equality, G.A. Cohen argues that justice requires an uncompromising commitment to equality.1 Cohen also argues, however, that justice must be sensitive to other values, including a genuine concern for individual freedom and the welfare of the community. Our question is * John Thrasher is currently a Ph.D. candidate in philosophy at the University of Arizona specializing in political philosophy and normative ethics. He has published papers on con- tractarianism, Epicurus, social evolution, and the virtue of justice. ** Keith Hankins is a Ph.D. candidate in philosophy at the University of Arizona and is currently pursuing graduate studies in economics at Rutgers University. He works in politi- cal philosophy, social choice theory, and game theory. 1 This work is the product of both authors equally. The ideas were conceived of and developed in conversations over a period of several months. J. Thrasher and K. Hankins / Journal of Moral Philosophy (2013) 2 DOI 10.1163/17455243-4681035 whether the sensitivity of justice to values other than equality entails that we must sometimes make room for inequality in the name of justice. One of Cohen’s central claims in Rescuing Justice and Equality is that there is no inherent tension between freedom, equality, and Pareto (wel- fare).2 All three values, Cohen argues, are co-achievable. The purported tension between them, what he calls the Trilemma Argument, relies on the premise that people are not driven by sufficiently egalitarian motives. Cohen is concerned to dissolve the trilemma because it threatens the tight connection between justice and egalitarianism. If equality can only be pur- chased at the price of either freedom or welfare, it seems less attractive. Cohen’s argument rests on the claim that our motivational sets are not fixed. If “people believe in equality,” there is no real trilemma and, accord- ingly, our reasons for licensing inequality in the name of justice lose their force. Cohen refers to this idea—that justice requires us to adopt an egali- tarian ethos—as the Ethical Solution, and he suggests that it is capable of dissolving any worries that the trilemma argument presents for his brand of egalitarianism. We argue that Cohen’s understanding of what justice requires leaves little room for the commitment to individual freedom that lies at the heart of liberalism which he claims to share (even if he disagrees with liberals about its implications). As such, refusing to temper the demands of equal- ity generates manifestly unjust consequences. Although Cohen’s claim that justice requires individuals to adopt an egalitarian ethos has received much attention,3 our argument departs from other discussions of Cohen insofar as our aim is to show that, even by his own lights, Cohen’s Ethical Solution is not successful. We discuss the Trilemma Argument in §1 and the Ethical Solution in §2. There we suggest that the Ethical Solution fails by developing an informal impossibility proof drawn from an example that Cohen uses to illustrate his argument. Cohen’s proposed resolution of the trilemma implies that for an individual to be free she must be able to make at least some choices in 2 Cohen’s use of “Pareto” sometimes obscures the fact that “Pareto” is not itself a value, but rather a principle that governs how we ought to evaluate different states that are meas- ured in terms of welfare, levels of preference satisfaction, or some other metric. The tension that Cohen is concerned with then is between freedom, equality, and ways of promoting welfare. 3 See especially Michael Titelbaum who agrees with Cohen that Rawls has good reasons to accept that justice requires individuals to adopt a certain ethos, but argues that such an ethos would not look like the one Cohen sketches. Michael G. Titelbaum, ‘What Would a Rawlsian Ethos of Justice Look Like?,’ Philosophy & Public Affairs, 36 (2008), pp. 289–322. J. Thrasher and K. Hankins / Journal of Moral Philosophy (2013) DOI 10.1163/17455243-4681035 3 accordance with her own beliefs and values. The idea that individuals must have space to live their own lives is further supported by his discussion of personal prerogatives and the role that appeals to these prerogatives play in justifying our practices. Each person, he argues, has “the right to be something other than an engine for the welfare of other people: we are not nothing but slaves to social justice.”4 In §3, we argue that Cohen’s discus- sion of prerogatives and his concern with dissolving the trilemma shows that costs to individual freedom are not easily borne—even for an egalitar- ian as uncompromising as Cohen. If the Ethical Solution fails then, as we argue it does, then Cohen cannot have all he wants and his criticism of lib- eralism loses much of its force. To show that the Ethical Solution does indeed fail, in §4 we develop a second impossibility proof which draws upon an example borrowed from Aristophanes. There we argue that because freedom, equality, and Pareto will not always be co-achievable, a genuine commitment to each necessarily requires making trade-offs. In §5, we conclude that a genuine commitment to respecting individual freedom means that inequalities will sometimes be justified in the name of justice. 1. The Trilemma Argument At the heart of Rescuing Justice and Equality is a claim that freedom, equal- ity, and welfare are co-achievable.5 Justice involves a commitment to all three values, but does not require trade-offs between them. Cohen uses a number of examples to support this claim. Each example compares various states of affairs, distinguished by how hard certain individuals decide to work or what occupations they decide to take up, and asks how they fare as measured against various metrics. Although Cohen does not himself utilize these tools, the structure of his examples makes them especially amenable to analysis using some of the tools of social choice theory.6 Utilizing these tools we can compare, as Cohen does, various states of affairs and ask whether they can be achieved consistently with a range of suitably 4 G.A. Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality (Harvard University Press, 2008), p. 10. 5 Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality, pp. 181–225. 6 We are largely following an approach derived from the application of social choice theory to ethics pioneered by Amartya Sen, but this basic approach does not require all of the assumptions of traditional social choice theory. For a similar axiomatic treatment of related issues, see: Michael Huemer, ‘Non-Egalitarianism,’ Philosophical Studies, 114 (2003), 147–171. J. Thrasher and K. Hankins / Journal of Moral Philosophy (2013) 4 DOI 10.1163/17455243-4681035 formalized ideals. This is helpful because it delivers a degree of precision that Cohen’s arguments (persuasive as they might be) otherwise lack. Ultimately, however, by developing an informal impossibility proof we will argue, contra Cohen, that freedom, equality, and Pareto, as metrics for eval- uating states of affairs cannot always be mutually satisfied. As a result, if justice is to incorporate each metric it must include a mechanism for bal- ancing them in cases where they conflict. Before we look at the proof itself, though, we first need to define the dif- ferent metrics in question and, because many critics are likely to object that the social choice approach we adopt is foreign to Cohen, say a few things to defend our approach. Although, as we suggested above, Cohen does not explicitly use the framework of social choice theory, his examples are set up in a way that mimics the structure of problems analyzed in the social choice literature and his analysis of these examples sometimes parallels the social choice approach we utilize. More importantly, Cohen discusses in detail Amartya Sen’s famous argument for the impossibility of Paretian liberalism.7 Sen, of course, explicitly utilizes the sort of social choice approach we adopt, and Cohen’s discussion of Sen clearly suggests that he takes Sen’s argument to bear on the thesis he wishes to defend.8 We take it, then, that Cohen has opened the door for the use of these tools in analyzing his own argument. Turning to the formalized metrics we will utilize, for welfare we use the notion of weak Pareto described by Sen and others. Following Sen, the weak Pareto condition states that “if every individual prefers an alternative x to another alternative y, then society must prefer x to y.”9 This is clearly the Pareto condition Cohen has in mind and it implies that for justice to be consistent with Pareto it cannot identify a state of affairs as just when there are alternative states available that are unanimously preferred to it.10 Moving on to freedom, in his discussion of the trilemma argument Cohen focuses on freedom of occupational choice. Freedom, he writes, requires “that people not be coerced into particular jobs, whether by direct state order or by something else that also deserves to be called coercive.”11 7 Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality, pp. 187–188. 8 Amartya Sen, ‘The Impossibility of a Paretian Liberal,’ The Journal of Political Economy, 78 (1970), 152–157. 9 Sen, ‘The Impossibility of a Paretian Liberal,’ p. 153. 10 Cohen writes: “The relevant Pareto requirement is the (weak) one that condemns pre- serving a state of affairs in which everyone can be made better off,” Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality, p. 184. 11 Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality, p. 184. Of course, Cohen is not interested only in freedom of occupational choice, he merely uses it to illustrate his argument, but if we can J. Thrasher and K. Hankins / Journal of Moral Philosophy (2013) DOI 10.1163/17455243-4681035 5 Utilizing our approach, however, requires something more formal and so for our freedom metric we again borrow a metric from Sen, namely his notion of minimal liberalism.12 Following Sen, this condition states that for every individual A, there is at least one pair of alternatives {x, y} such that if A prefers x to y, society must prefer x to y, in the sense that it cannot coerce A into choosing y over x.13 While there is considerable debate about the definitions of freedom utilized by Sen, we think the notion captures what Cohen has in mind within the context of his example.14 For instance, although Cohen criticizes the conclusion that Sen draws from his proof, he does not argue that the minimal liberalism condition is an inadequate model of liberal rights.15 Further, a simple example illustrates that this condition is analogous to the basic conception of freedom of occupation Cohen sketches. If Roxanne prefers one job over another and both are offered to her, free- dom dictates that society cannot coerce her into choosing her less preferred job. It is in that sense that her decision about what job to take is decisive.16 The third value, equality, is the hardest to specify because Cohen’s dis- cussion of it is surprisingly unclear. Cohen writes that “egalitarians like [him] think that justice is served only if people’s access to desirable condi- tions of life is equal,” but he suggests that for the purposes of the trilemma Argument, “the relevant equality might be only that no one is substantially better off than others are with respect to both income and job satisfac- tion.”17 The challenge then is to specify what it would mean for access to the desirable conditions of life to be equal, or for some to be substantially better off than others. Fortunately, Cohen spends much of the book discuss- ing Rawls’ difference principle that lends itself well to formalization, and Cohen defends a particularly demanding interpretation of the difference show that there exists an unavoidable tension between this sort of freedom and equality, then our argument generalizes to freedom more broadly construed. 12 Sen, ‘The Impossibility of a Paretian Liberal,’ p. 154. 13 Note that the Freedom condition also requires that A be free to decide which pair of alternatives she is decisive over. This is necessary to ensure that the condition is substan- tive; otherwise, the condition could be trivially met by providing an individual with deci- siveness over two worthless alternatives. 14 For an overview of the debate on Sen’s argument of the impossibility of a Paretian liberalism and Sen’s responses to critics see: Amartya Sen, ‘Rights: Formulation and Consequences,’ in Rationality and Freedom (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2002), pp. 439–461. 15 See Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality, p. 187. 16 In the case where Roxanne is presented with multiple job offers, freedom requires that she be able to eliminate at least one from consideration, so that she cannot be forced to accept a job that she least prefers. 17 Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality, p. 184. J. Thrasher and K. Hankins / Journal of Moral Philosophy (2013) 6 DOI 10.1163/17455243-4681035 principle that is easier still to formalize.18 Following Cohen’s discussion of the difference principle, we assume that equality means maximizing, by their own lights, the condition of the least well off.19 On this definition, equality implies that given a pair of alternatives {x, y} if x maximizes the condition of the least well off, then x is more just than y. As a result, at least as a matter of justice, society ought to prefer x to y. While there is much more that can and should be said about equality, this definition provides us with the specificity required to analyze the trilemma argument and Cohen’s proposed solution to it. Before moving on it is also important to say something about the con- cept of preference we utilize. There is often some confusion about what it means to prefer one alternative to another, and indeed, Cohen is somewhat unclear about what he means by preference. In order to avoid confusion, then, we employ a technical sense of preference that is clearer than the ordinary notion. Although the ordinary notion of preference allows us to say that we can sometimes choose an act that we might not prefer to do (which perhaps because we are required to do by some type of duty), the technical sense of preference we employ subsumes all considerations that lead to action.20 This notion of preference is both essentially comparative and all things considered, so that to prefer something is to prefer it to some- thing else.21 18 The version of the difference principle that Cohen favors requires that we maximize the well-being (or primary goods available to) the worst off, that labor burden be included in the distributive metric, and that the demands of the difference principle extend to individu- als’ actions and decisions as opposed to being restricted to the structure of our major social institutions. See: Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality, Chapter 1, Part III and Chapter 2. 19 In utilizing this variant of the difference principle as our equality metric, however, we do not mean to be taking a stand on the question of whether the difference principle licenses inequalities to some that might be necessary as incentives to induce them to do work that redounds to the benefit of others. Further, we do not mean to be claiming that the difference principle is ultimately the best way of understanding what equality demands of us. Cohen clearly thought that equality was best understood as requiring that persons have “equal access to advantages.” For analyzing the trilemma argument, however, using the difference principle as a metric of equality is sufficient and does not contradict the spirit of Cohen’s argument. 20 One account, among many, of the technical sense of preference employed here is found in S.I. Benn and G.W. Mortimore, ‘Technical Models of Rational Choice,’ in Rationality and the Social Sciences, 1976, pp. 160–161. This is also the account of preference normally employed in the social choice literature. A good recent discussion can also be found in Daniel M. Hausman, Preferences, Value, Choice, and Welfare (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011), Chapters 1 & 2 . 21 There is considerable philosophical debate on the nature and grounding of prefer- ences as well as their relationship to psychological states such as beliefs and desires. On these questions, we remain silent. J. Thrasher and K. Hankins / Journal of Moral Philosophy (2013) DOI 10.1163/17455243-4681035 7 Having described the approach we will use, we can now turn our atten- tion to the primary example that Cohen uses to illustrate the trilemma. Cohen’s example involves a person that we call Epicurean Doctor, who enjoys gardening, but will work as a doctor if her wage is sufficiently high.22 Epicurean Doctor is willing to give up the pleasure and satisfaction she gets from gardening if she is paid $30,000 more dollars to be a doctor, but if offered the same wage for each job, say $20,000, she prefers to be a gardener. Whatever she chooses, Cohen stipulates, she is much better off than most other people are in her society, and further, doctoring imposes no hardships on her over and above the fact that she prefers gardening. Her society, however, needs doctors and so society would most prefer to pay Epicurean Doctor only $20,000 to work as a doctor, but would also prefer to have her work as a doctor at $50,000 than to have her spend her days gardening. Assuming nobody else cares whether Epicurean Doctor is able to pursue her passion for gardening, and (to simplify things) if society as a whole is responsible for directly paying doctors, then we have a divergence between Epicurean Doctor’s preferences and society’s preferences.23 As we suggested above, we can model justice as a social choice rule that ranks the three occupational choices that confront Epicurean Doctor given her preferences and everyone else’s which are represented in Table 1 below: 22 Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality, chap. 5 section 2. 23 In a forthcoming review of Rescuing Japa Pallikkathayil argues that it is unclear on what grounds Cohen is committed to caring about the absolute condition of the worst off (or anyone for that matter). As such it’s not clear how justice should constrain the choice of occupations with equal wages (or levels of welfare). For instance, Pallikkathayil argues that although Cohen sometimes suggests that a commitment to equality is enough to motivate the choice of, for example, more socially useful occupations, this seems like a mistake. See Japa Pallikkathayil, ‘Review of G.A. Cohen’s Rescuing Justice and Equality,’ Journal of Philosophy (Forthcoming). Table 1 Epicurean Doctor Everyone Else (a) Doctor at $50,000 (c) Doctor at $20,000 (b) Gardener at $20,000 (a) Doctor at $50,000 (c) Doctor at $20,000 (b) Gardener at $20,000 J. Thrasher and K. Hankins / Journal of Moral Philosophy (2013) 8 DOI 10.1163/17455243-4681035 Epicurean Doctor has the preference ordering a > b > c, while Everyone Else has the preference ordering c > a > b. The question that the proponent of the trilemma argument forces us to ask is how justice responds to these divergent preferences, and in particular whether a social choice rule mod- eling justice can mutually satisfy the constraints presented by equality, freedom, and Pareto as we have defined them? Both Epicurean Doctor and Everyone Else prefer a to b, so according to Pareto b should not be chosen over a. However, option c is also on the Pareto frontier because there is no alternative that everyone prefers to c. We can say then that the Pareto principle is not decisive here because both a and c are compatible with it. Alternatively, if we appeal to freedom, per- haps claiming that Epicurean Doctor has a right to freedom of occupation, then we must make (some of) Epicurean Doctor’s preferences concerning her occupation decisive and a will be the likely winner.24 Appealing to equality, however, yields a different result. If we assume that alternative c (doctoring at $20,000) maximizes the condition of the least well off, then even though Epicurean Doctor ranks option c last, it is the option picked out by the equality metric.25 We summarize these outcomes in Table 2 below: 24 Strictly speaking freedom picks out either a or b depending upon which pair of alter- natives {a, c} or {b, c} Epicurean Doctor is decisive over. The important point is that freedom effectively rules out c and ultimately yields a as the social choice either directly (if Epicurean Doctor is decisive over a and c) or indirectly (if Epicurean Doctor is decisive over b and c, in which case freedom picks out b and Pareto leads us to a because a > b by everyone). Note that we can ignore the pair {a, b} because freedom allows Epicurean Doctor to decide which pair she is decisive over and because society prefers that she be a doctor at $50,000 (a) to gardening at $20,000 (b), so there is no need for her to exercise her decisiveness over that pair. Our earlier discussion of Sen’s minimal liberalism condition explains why it is neces- sary that Epicurean Doctor be allowed to decide which pair she is decisive over, namely that if our freedom condition is to be substantive, Epicurean Doctor must not only be decisive over at least one pair of alternatives, but she must be free (within some substantial range) to choose which pair of alternatives she should be decisive over. 25 We grant for the sake of argument that this is a reasonable assumption since society needs doctors and c involves the Epicurean Doctor, working for less money, thus leaving society with more money which it might then use to benefit the least well off in other ways. Table 2 Freedom a (or b) Equality c Pareto a or c J. Thrasher and K. Hankins / Journal of Moral Philosophy (2013) DOI 10.1163/17455243-4681035 9 Referring to Table 2 we can see that freedom and Pareto are compatible since they each yield a as an eligible social choice. Pareto and equality are, similarly, compatible since they each leave c in the eligible set. Freedom and equality, however, do not yield compatible choices. If we appeal to equality, freedom is swamped. Everyone Else becomes decisive over the pairs {a, c} and {b, c} and is thus able to dictate both Epicurean Doctor’s job and salary. This result suggests that an uncompromising commitment to equality requires that we sacrifice freedom in cases where an individual’s preferences conflict with the interests of the least well off. Alternatively, if we appeal to freedom and allow (again, some of) Epicurean Doctor’s prefer- ences to be decisive, then the least well off will be worse off than they might otherwise be. This is the deep tension between the values that concern lib- erals versus the values that concern egalitarians. Because Cohen is con- cerned with showing that a commitment to equality does not require us to sacrifice freedom, we focus on the former result and in the next section we look at his proposed solution to this problem. 2. The Ethical Solution As Cohen recognizes, his example involving the Epicurean Doctor is analo- gous to Sen’s Prude/Lewd example from his argument for the impossibility of Paretian liberalism. Contra Sen, however, Cohen argues that it is a mis- take to think that minimal rights must conflict with Pareto or, carrying the point over to his own example, with equality. Cohen’s primary contention is that “liberalism does not require that you exercise the sovereignty it grants in accordance with your other-things-equal first preferences.”26 He also argues however that the notion of liberalism embodied in Sen’s “minimal liberalism” and captured by the freedom principle we have used, is not at all similar to the liberalism that he claims to share with Dworkin and Rawls.27 With respect to his second point, Cohen is simply mistaken. To be valu- able, freedom or liberal rights must give significant weight to protecting individuals from having the preferences of others imposed on them. Of course, an individual may decide not to exercise a right in a given case— Cohen is right about this much—but to be significant, that decision must presuppose the individual’s ability to exercise the right should she desire.28 26 Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality, p. 187. 27 Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality, p. 188. 28 It is true that elsewhere Cohen famously characterizes freedom in terms of ability, and in his example the Epicurean doctor is surely able to choose the occupation of her choice. Our J. Thrasher and K. Hankins / Journal of Moral Philosophy (2013) 10 DOI 10.1163/17455243-4681035 To say that a minimally liberal set of rights conflicts with Pareto and equal- ity then is to say that if some individuals exercised their rights either Pareto or equality must be sacrificed. Indeed, this was the point of Sen’s original argument, namely that rights and social welfare will not always coincide, and it is only once we understand this point on a formal level that we are led to more substantive philosophical questions concerning which values justice requires us to be sensitive to and in what kinds of situations.29 Cohen is making a deeper point as well though, viz. that the demands of justice extend beyond those placed on the basic structure of society, and it is on this deeper point that his main line of argument against the problem posed by the trilemma rests.30 Cohen’s argument is that if the decisions we made in our individual lives were guided by a belief in equality, the tri- lemma dissolves. Justice, he argues, requires us to internalize certain values and once we do so, our preference for exercising our rights in ways that generate the sort of conflict the proponent of the trilemma worries about will vanish. Cohen refers to this as the Ethical Solution and motivates it with the following imaginary exchange: The trilemmist says: “We shouldn’t be egalitarians, because equality requires a sacrifice of either Pareto or freedom.” To which I reply: “That isn’t so, because, if we were egalitarians, we should be sacrificing neither.” And that reply isn’t trivial.31 Cohen’s argument is that once the Epicurean Doctor realizes the impor- tance of equality she would (or should) change her preferences. If she really cared about equality, freedom would not be an issue. point is simply that if freedom is to be substantively valuable, justice must carve out a range of choices, from which an individual is free to choose, consistent with the demands of justice. 29 Indeed, this point, and the larger point that the point of theorizing about justice is to provide practical guidance in alleviating suffering and solving disputes is the primary thesis of Sen’s recent book and has also been powerfully articulated by David Schmidtz. See Amartya Sen, The Idea of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2009) and David Schmidtz, ‘When Justice Matters,’ Ethics, 117 (2007), pp. 433–459. 30 This is one of the main thrusts of Cohen’s book and is an issue about which there has been much debate. See: Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality, chap. 4; Liam B. Murphy, ‘Institutions and the Demands of Justice,’ Philosophy & Public Affairs, 27 (1998), 251–291; Thomas W. Pogge, ‘On the Site of Distributive Justice: Reflections on Cohen and Murphy,’ Philosophy & Public Affairs, 29 (2000), 137–169; A.J. Julius, ‘Basic Structure and the Value of Equality,’ Philosophy & Public Affairs, 31 (2003), 321–355; Thomas Porter, ‘The Division of Moral Labour and the Basic Structure Restriction,’ Politics, Philosophy & Economics, 8 (2009), 173–199; Kok-Chor Tan, Justice, Institutions, and Luck: The Site, Ground, and Scope of Equality (Oxford University Press, USA, 2012). 31 Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality, p. 196. J. Thrasher and K. Hankins / Journal of Moral Philosophy (2013) DOI 10.1163/17455243-4681035 11 Of course, the Epicurean Doctor might simply respond that if Everyone Else really cared about freedom, they would leave her alone to pursue her preferred profession without interference. In either case, though, solving the problem this way merely sidesteps the serious philosophical questions concerning how social justice should accommodate competing values. Cohen’s argument is that in a truly just society, people’s preferences would align with equality and, hence, it would never conflict with the other two metrics. This amounts to saying that if the Epicurean Doctor cared about equality she would prefer to work as a doctor for $20,000 rather than gar- den or work as a doctor for a higher wage. Her preference ordering would change from a > b > c to c > a > b and since her preferences would now be the same as Everyone Else’s no trilemma would arise. We say this approach sidesteps the difficult philosophical issues at hand, because it is hard to see how it shows that the trilemma is not really a problem. In this case, justice free from conflict is merely the product of philosophical fiat. Cohen “solves” the trilemma argument by stipulating that it never arises.32 For his solution to be of general interest, Cohen needs to show that the preference profiles that give rise to the trilemma are inadmissible. Essentially, Cohen needs to show that we have good reason to reject the unrestricted domain condition that we implicitly assumed in the Epicurean Doctor example.33 Sen describes unrestricted domain as the condition that “every logically possible set of individual orderings is included in the domain of the collective choice rule.”34 In other words, no individuals or preference orderings should be excluded from the scope of the collective choice rule— in this case, the rule being used to model the requirements of justice. Of course, it is by no means obvious that justice must license the range of 32 Note that the problem is more dramatic still. For Cohen’s solution not only requires that individuals be motivated to pursue egalitarian policies, but the same egalitarian poli- cies; otherwise the problem of divergence of preferences will arise even assuming an egali- tarian ethos. Rawls in particular, whose animating concern was the problem posed by the fact of reasonable pluralism, would have been particularly attuned to this worry. 33 Cohen’s solution to the trilemma exploits the well-known fact in the social choice lit- erature that only certain preference profiles generate the paradoxes of social choice that the famous impossibility theorems threaten. Like Cohen here, many have attempted to defang the threat of various impossibility theorems by weakening the unrestricted domain assump- tion that Arrow’s impossibility theorem, among others, relies upon. Unfortunately, one of the most dispiriting lessons in social choice has been that many forms of impossibility are resil- ient in the face of a substantial degree of weakening of their axioms. Furthermore, the type of restriction that Cohen proposes is not trivial as he is essentially proposing restricting the domain of individual preferences so that they are identical to the set of social preferences. 34 Sen, ‘The Impossibility of the Paretian Liberal,’ p. 153. J. Thrasher and K. Hankins / Journal of Moral Philosophy (2013) 12 DOI 10.1163/17455243-4681035 preferences that the unrestricted domain condition allows, particularly if justice requires (as Cohen thinks it does) that individuals internalize a cer- tain ethos, and so Cohen’s strategy perhaps looks promising. In the next section, however, we will see that Cohen lacks the resources needed to restrict the domain of acceptable preferences to the extent required by his solution to the trilemma. 3. Vacations, Sick Days, and Prerogatives In his earlier work, Cohen argues in favor of a principle of symmetrical jus- tification for coercion.35 In Rescuing, however, his discussion of justifica- tion is framed first in terms of something he calls the interpersonal test,36 and later in terms of the idea of a personal prerogative first sketched by Samuel Scheffler and subsequently developed by David Estlund.37 Cohen begins the trilemma chapter trilemma with the observation that the demands of egalitarian justice must fall “within the constraint of a reason- able personal prerogative, deference to which informs the whole of the fol- lowing discussion”—only a moral rigorist, he argues, could deny a place for such a prerogative, and he affirms that he is not such a rigorist.38 Prerogatives are important because valuing the freedom of persons to pursue a conception of the good requires that they have considerable room within to make decisions about their life and prerogatives provide people with this space.39 Prerogatives protecting occupational choice are espe- cially important in this regard. No less important is being free to choose how to trade off time spent working with time spent with one’s friends and 35 G.A. Cohen, Self-ownership, Freedom, and Equality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), pp. 56–57. 36 See Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality, chap. 1, Section  5. According to Cohen, as free and equal members of a moral community our relationships ought to be structured by a norm of comprehensive justification and a necessary condition of comprehensive justifi- cation is that arguments be capable of passing the interpersonal test, where this requires that an argument must be capable of providing justification under any and all dialogical conditions. In other words, an argument’s ability to provide justification must be indepen- dent of both who is presenting it and to whom it is being presented. 37 David Estlund, ‘Liberalism, Equality, and Fraternity in Cohen’s Critique of Rawls,’ Journal of Political Philosophy, 6 (1998), p. 99 and Samuel Scheffler, The Rejection of Consequentialism (New York: Oxford University Press, 1982). 38 Cohen writes “I do not wish to reject … what Samuel Scheffler has called an “agent- centered prerogative,” Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality, p. 61. 39 This point is especially clear in the case of love and relationships, which we discuss in section 5. J. Thrasher and K. Hankins / Journal of Moral Philosophy (2013) DOI 10.1163/17455243-4681035 13 family, or pursuing other interests and passions. Treating people as free then requires that individuals have the prerogative to make their own choices about how to live their lives even if this means that there will be some who do worse than they otherwise might. While Cohen accepts that there is a place for a modest personal preroga- tive within his view of justice, there are two ways of understanding such prerogatives. On one hand, prerogatives can be conceived of as “vacations” from the demands of justice. Vacations are justified departures from the requirements of justice that allow individuals a certain amount of space to freely pursue their own projects, regardless of how these pursuits relate to distributive justice.40 Conceived of in this way, prerogatives prevent justice from being all-encompassing. Alternatively, prerogatives can be thought of as “sick days.” Thought of this way, prerogatives are excuses for failing to live up to the demands of justice. However, just as it would perhaps be bet- ter if individuals didn’t have to take sick days from work, it would also be more just if people minimized the number of prerogatives taken to depart from the demands of justice. It sounds odd though to say that we should treat prerogatives just as we do sick days. This requires us to think that individuals’ pursuing their own projects is something to regret—a necessary evil. Acting in accordance with justice, on this model, is a kind of Stakhanovism.41 If this is Cohen’s view, he is in danger of repeating the mistake that Bernard Williams and Rawls attri- bute to utilitarianism: that it does not take the separateness of persons seri- ously, viewing people instead as mere nodes for the fulfillment of justice. To make the distinction we have drawn even starker, note that individu- als are often expected and even encouraged to take vacations from work, lest they allow their work to cause them to lose sight of the other important things in life. Although one’s occupation is often bound up with one’s iden- tity, and in many cases helps to give life meaning, what makes the freedom to choose one’s occupation important are the myriad values, interests, and larger-scale projects that individuals have which give them reasons to shape their identities in various ways. While these are issues that Cohen is sensitive to, unfortunately he does not fully appreciate the constraints they impose on a view like his. Although he accepts that justice must make room for a reasonable personal prerogative, he tells us little about what 40 For a more complete discussion of a view like this, see: David Estlund, ‘Liberalism, Equality, and Fraternity in Cohen’s Critique of Rawls,’ p. 99. 41 ‘Stakhanovism’ refers to the ideology of the Stakhanovite movement of the 1930s in the Soviet Union under Stalin. The movement was inspired by the example of Aleksei Stakhanov a miner who, in 1935, mined 14 times his quota of coal in one day. J. Thrasher and K. Hankins / Journal of Moral Philosophy (2013) 14 DOI 10.1163/17455243-4681035 falls within the scope of such a prerogative nor, as we have seen, does he tell us how such prerogatives mediate the demands of justice.42 This second point is particularly important, for if prerogatives are best conceived of along the vacation model as we have argued they should be, then it is hard to see how Cohen can constrain the domain of admissible preferences to the degree required to get his ethical solution off the ground. This is because the only way the ethical solution succeeds is if individuals could come to have such a strong egalitarian ethos that their occupational preferences coincide with what would best promote the needs of the least well off. As we will see in the next two sections though, even if individuals could come to adopt such an equality driven ethos, there are reasons to doubt whether they should. Before exploring this argument, though, it is important to first clarify why the ethical solution succeeds only if the domain of free choice is severely curtailed. The problem is that prerogatives license inequalities and we have good reason to concede that individuals have prerogatives within which they are free to act. Cohen admits as much. His disagreement with those like Estlund and Scheffler who have drawn attention to the inequality generating feature of prerogatives is directed solely at the amount of inequality that reasonable prerogatives license and the way in which they do so.43 Cohen accepts that prerogatives allow individuals to justifiably make choices that generate inequality, but contra Estlund he argues that the amount of inequality that is thus justified is not extensive. This is a debate about the extent of inequality that is justified, though, and not a debate about whether it is justified. Similarly, Cohen emphasizes that the prerogative justification provides a different sort of justification for inequality than the incentive argument that grounds the difference principle, but this too does little to cut against the claim that some inequalities will be justified because it only 42 In the introduction to Rescuing, for instance, Cohen points out that there are many forms of motivation lying on a spectrum that stretches from unrestrained market-maximiz- ing at one end to fully self-sacrificial restraint favoring the worst off at the other. He then argues that the first extreme is permitted by Rawls, something that he finds absurd, but he also argues that the second extreme isn’t required because requiring such self-sacrifice is “excluded by a legitimate personal prerogative.” Because individuals have their own lives to lead, Cohen suggests “they are therefore permitted to strike a balance between the claims of the difference principle and their own legitimate concerns.” The difficulty, on Cohen’s view, is that what constitutes an appropriate balance is a “vague matter.” Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality, pp. 10–11. 43 See Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality, pp. 387–389 Section  4 of the General Appendix, “Incentives and Prerogatives.” J. Thrasher and K. Hankins / Journal of Moral Philosophy (2013) DOI 10.1163/17455243-4681035 15 speaks to the question of how those inequalities are justified.44 This is important because our argument has been directed at Cohen’s claim that equality, freedom, and Pareto are not in conflict. We have denied Cohen’s claim, and in doing so, what we have argued is that Cohen must license some inequality if he is to maintain his commitment to freedom. What we have not tried to say, however, is how much inequality he must make room for. 4. The Women of Athens In the “Ecclesiazusae,” Aristophanes depicts an Athens racked by war and deprivation, having been run into the ground by the men. In response, the women of the city take over the legislative assembly and, in an effort to save Athens from total ruin, their first act is to legislate absolute equality between all Athenians. Their leader Praxagora decrees that, “Mankind should possess in common the instruments of happiness. Henceforth pri- vate property comes to an end …”45 The plan, as Praxagora elaborates, is to “destroy [the old] morality”46 and supplant it with a new ethos, the hope being that by working together and owning all things in common Athenians could come to build a society on a foundation of equality. Praxagora is, like Cohen, ultimately concerned with equality of welfare, not equality of money and because one of the aspects of life that can con- tribute the most to happiness and welfare is love, she becomes concerned about the vast inequities of love that naturally exist. Recognizing that it is hard for the old, the ugly, and the awkward to compete with those younger, prettier, and smoother for the affections of potential lovers, the women outlaw marriage in the city and even go so far as to make it illegal for the young and pretty to have their turn at love without first allowing the older and uglier a chance.47 In one scene, a pretty young girl is waiting for her lover while an old woman stands close by. Eventually the young man arrives, seeking the 44 It is also worth noting that in his reply to critics Cohen eventually acknowledges, fol- lowing Estlund, that prerogatives could serve to legitimate certain deployments of the incentive argument, his argument with Estlund on that point being that there is simply no trace of such an argument to be found in Rawls’ work. 45 Aristophanes, ‘Ecclesiazusae,’ in The Complete Plays of Aristophanes, ed. by Moses Hadas, Bantam Classic (New York: Bantam Classics, 1981), p. 438. 46 Aristophanes, ‘Ecclesiazusae,’ p. 439. 47 Aristophanes, ‘Ecclesiazusae,’ p. 457. J. Thrasher and K. Hankins / Journal of Moral Philosophy (2013) 16 DOI 10.1163/17455243-4681035 young girl. The older woman, spying her chance, demands that the young man obey the new law. Horrified at what justice now requires of him, the young man tries to trick the old woman, but to no avail. She prevails and drags him off into her room. At just that moment, though, an older, uglier woman shows up to claim her right and the first woman is forced to give him over to her older and uglier competitor. Naturally, as the second old woman is taking the young man away a third appears, older and uglier still. As the third old woman says, “I’m older, and I’m uglier; consequently this boy belongs to me.”48 Given the multiplicity of women arranged in a hier- archy of unattractiveness, the young man will have to work his way down the line if he intends to ever be with his lover. While the young man has no interest in being with any of the old women, alas, his wishes are irrelevant. If he could do as he wished and be only with his beloved, the old women would be much worse off in relation to the young couple. From the point of view of justice, at least as instantiated by the women of Athens, this is unacceptable. If the young man wishes to pur- sue the girl, he does indeed “belong” to the oldest woman first, because her happiness and welfare overrule his freedom to choose his partners. There is a sense, then, in which the young man has become merely a means to the old women’s satisfaction. This case clearly illustrates what it is like for indi- viduals to be treated merely as material for the fulfillment of justice. What makes it particularly compelling though is that Cohen is clearly committed to thinking that it is inconsistent with justice to treat individuals in this way.49 As we did with the case of the Epicurean Doctor, we can formalize Aristophanes’ story. In the Aristophanes case, however, unlike the Epicu- rean Doctor case, we have many preference orderings rather than simply two. Furthermore, the preferences range over who may be with whom in a romantic situation and so the example is even starker than Cohen’s origi- nal case insofar as it involves action that is even more personal than occu- pational choice.50 48 Aristophanes, ‘Ecclesiazusae,’ p. 459. 49 Recall, for instance, Cohen’s claim from the introduction to Rescuing that individuals have the right to be something other than engines for the welfare of other people. 50 Aside from the already discussed prerogative, there is no reason in principle why Cohen should hold that the demands of justice should not apply to romantic choice, espe- cially if romantic partners are importantly related to welfare. We need not be committed to the claim that Cohen would have us all be egalitarians in romantic matters though. Rather, the point of the example is simply to illustrate the tension between freedom and equality and thus the need to invoke a prerogative or some other mechanism for resolving this tension. J. Thrasher and K. Hankins / Journal of Moral Philosophy (2013) DOI 10.1163/17455243-4681035 17 In order to simplify things, in what follows, we represent this situation as involving three persons, though the older and uglier women that enter later could easily be incorporated without changing the result. The Young Man prefers to be with the Young Woman and only the Young Woman. We can call this state of affairs, x. Nevertheless, if he cannot be with just the Young Woman, he is willing to be with the Old Woman first and then the Young Woman. He finds the prospect of being with the Old Woman objec- tionable, but he is willing to pay that price for love if he must. We call this state of affairs where the Young Man will be with the Old Woman first, and then the Young Woman, y. The worst state of affairs for the Young Man is to miss the opportunity to be with his beloved entirely. This state of affairs involves everyone leaving the scene without having any romantic involve- ment at all. We can call this state of affairs z. Thus, the Young Man’s prefer- ence ordering in this situation is: x > y > z. The Young Woman’s first preference is also to be with her lover, the Young Man, without any interference from the Old Woman, and so she pre- fers x to all other alternatives. The thought of her lover with the Old Woman angers her so much, however, that she would prefer z to y even though this means she would have to forgo the affection of her lover. The Young Woman’s preference ordering, then, is: x > z > y. Finally, the Old Woman prefers y to all other states of affairs, but would be so wrought with jealousy and envy if the Young Woman were able to have the Young Man to herself that she prefers z to x and so her preference ordering is: y > z > x.51 These orderings are represented in Table 3 below: 51 We assume for the sake of argument that the Old Woman’s preferences accurately track her welfare. As we will see in the next section, though, there are perhaps problems with making this assumption that in turn give us further reason to doubt the efficacy of Cohen’s proposed solution to the trilemma. Table 3 Young Man Young Woman Old Woman x x y y z z z y x As in the Epicurean Doctor case, we have a dilemma. We say dilemma, rather than trilemma here because in this situation, every alternative satis- fies the Pareto principle and so it cannot conflict with our other principles. There is no pair of alternatives such that one alternative is preferred to the other by everyone. Both the Young Man and the Young Woman prefer x to J. Thrasher and K. Hankins / Journal of Moral Philosophy (2013) 18 DOI 10.1163/17455243-4681035 y while the Old Woman prefers y to x and similarly, the Young Man and Young Woman prefer x to z while the Old Woman prefers z to x.52 On the other hand, the Young Man and the Old Woman both prefer y to z, while the Young Woman prefers z to y. There is no way then to reconcile their respective preferences with both equality and the requirement that each individual be decisive over at least one pair.53 5. The Demands of Equality In the “Ecclesiazusae,” the women of Athens deem equality to be the unique collective choice rule consistent with justice. The result is comical. Their uncompromising commitment to equality threatens to undermine even their most basic freedoms. We should be worried then by the fact that Aristophanes’ dilemma parallels the trilemma argument, particularly since Cohen’s proposal that the trilemma can be dissolved if only we could embrace an ethos of equality is not offered in jest. In light of Aristophanes’ dilemma, we must ask whether Cohen’s ethical solution really allows us to express an uncompromising commitment to equality without becoming “slaves to social justice.” Let us assume, following Cohen’s suggestion, that the characters in our example borrowed from Aristophanes have become perfectly committed to equality so that the young couple’s preferences come to coincide with the Old Woman’s. Their respective preference orderings can then be repre- sented as follows: 52 To get this result we need not assume transitivity, only quasi-transitivity since we are only dealing with strict preference orderings without indifference. 53 Note that the primary problem presented by this particular set of preference profiles is that the Young Woman ranks y, the option required by equality, as her least preferred option. Table 4 Original Dilemma Cohen’s Revised Dilemma Young Man Young Woman Old Woman Young Man Young Woman Old Woman x x y y y y y z z z z z z y x x x x J. Thrasher and K. Hankins / Journal of Moral Philosophy (2013) DOI 10.1163/17455243-4681035 19 Note that the proposed revision of the parties’ preferences does indeed solve the problem, but as with the Epicurean Doctor case, it is only able to do this by changing the circumstances. Earlier we charged Cohen with avoiding the problem rather than confronting it. The point we now wish to make, though, is that Cohen himself gives us reason to think that we should be hesitant to adopt such an ethos. First, however, we must consider what can be said in favor of adopting such an ethos. There is a similarity for instance between this example and Cohen’s occasional approval of “everyone doing his or her bit” in war- time England.54 On Cohen’s view, despite the hardships that accompanied “doing one’s bit,” a certain amount of fellow feeling and patriotism moti- vated people to do more than they might have otherwise done and this is to be celebrated. It does not follow, however, that since people were moti- vated by fellow feeling that their hardships were no longer hardships. Indeed it is precisely because everyone “did their bit” in the face of these hardships that that fact is to be celebrated. Similarly, the Young Man, despite his newly acquired egalitarian ethos, will still find the prospect of being with the older women objectionable, but he will see it as his duty as well and so will perform the task in spite of this. He may even get a warm feeling knowing that he has done his duty. The problem we face is that in this case equality is providing the wrong kind of reason for action. Cohen opens the door to this argument in the final section of “The Freedom Objection.” Here, Cohen makes an intriguing argument against prostitution. Prostitution is wrong, Cohen argues, for the same reason that rape is wrong, namely because “the wanted thing is yielded for the wrong reason.”55 Of course, some might argue with this characterization of rape. It may not be merely sex that the rapist is after. Rape is, at least some of the time, an exercise of power and domination and not just a sexual act. Cohen argues, however, that it would be wrong to view rape merely as a “species of assault.”56 To think of rape in that way would be to base one’s disapproval of it on a “breach of self-ownership” and would make one indifferent to prostitution to the extent that prostitution is (at least sometimes) an expression of self-ownership. Cohen’s argument here is far from uncontroversial, but rather than dis- pute Cohen’s assessment of rape and prostitution we want to consider how Cohen’s claim puts pressure on his proposed solution to the trilemma. 54 Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality, p. 219. 55 Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality, p. 224. 56 Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality, p. 224. J. Thrasher and K. Hankins / Journal of Moral Philosophy (2013) 20 DOI 10.1163/17455243-4681035 In our Aristophanes example, the Young Man has a duty to have sex with the Old Woman if he ever wants to be with his lover. Of course, he does not love or desire the Old Woman and so, although he may be motivated to engage with her, this can only be because he has embraced his egalitarian ethos so completely. The Young Man’s commitment to egalitarianism may be commendable, but, like the prostitute, he is yielding the “wanted thing” for the wrong reasons. While the Young Man is not being forced to yield his body to the Old Woman because he is motivated to do it, his commitment to equality or justice does not translate into love or desire for the Old Woman. It follows, then, that if we are to condemn prostitution and rape along the lines that Cohen suggests, we should also condemn this particu- lar act of “yielding” for the same reasons. This is bad news for Cohen’s ethical solution, for it shows that even if adopting an egalitarian ethos could dissolve the trilemma, by Cohen’s own lights we sometimes have overrid- ing reasons not to do so. Sometimes, it seems, there are inequalities that it would be unjust to change. Of course, the defender of Cohen could argue that what an appropriate egalitarian ethos really requires of the young couple is that they simply refrain from being with one another. Thus, the Young Man would not be compelled to yield himself to the Old Woman for the wrong reasons, but the Old Woman would now have no reason to envy the young couple’s abil- ity to find love. This, we think, goes too far. While it perhaps does not make the young couple mere engines for the welfare of the older and less attrac- tive, it does threaten to swallow up any space they might have in which to live their own lives. More reasonably, Cohen could argue that romantic choices should fall within the purview of a personal prerogative. We do not disagree. The problem is that if Cohen grants that choosing one’s romantic partner should fall within the scope of a reasonable prerogative, then that romantic choices are protected in this way simply serves as proof that the commitment to equality is not, in the end, uncompromising. At this point we must consider whether we have given due weight to Cohen’s sensitivity to the distinction between the relation of the personal and impersonal on one hand and the relationship between justice and the personal on the other.57 The worry as we understand it is that Cohen’s sen- sitivity to this distinction mitigates much of the criticism that we have lev- ied against him. We appreciate Cohen’s sensitivity to issues like this. We recognize, for instance, that Cohen would prefer us not to be egalitarians about everything, least of all sex and love. We struggle to see though how 57 We thank an anonymous referee for this journal for raising this point. J. Thrasher and K. Hankins / Journal of Moral Philosophy (2013) DOI 10.1163/17455243-4681035 21 this insulates him from the charges we have laid at his feet. One reason is that it is hard to see how Cohen can draw a non-arbitrary line between those choices that do and those that do not fall within the scope of justice. After all, one of the main theses Cohen defends is that “the personal is political” and thus that the demands of justice extend to the sorts of deci- sions individuals make in their everyday lives. Indeed his entire criticism of Rawls rests on this claim. More importantly, however, we believe that there is good reason to think that something like a prerogative does not in fact compete with justice. There is a deep tension running through Cohen’s thought, though, that makes it unclear whether he can hold this view. Cohen recognizes that because individuals have their own lives to lead, neither justice nor equality can be all that matters. On one way of understanding things, this is not problematic because justice is simply one value among many. Indeed, Cohen suggests that “there is some justice that cannot, and some that should not, be implemented institutionally, or indeed, as Shakespeare’s Portia knew, at all.”58 On this view, we must make room for inequality in light of individuals’ reasonable personal prerogatives, but this is not a requirement of justice. Rather, as we argued in §3, it is a (potentially regret- table) situation that arises because these prerogatives lie outside the scope of justice. As Cohen also argues, though, the label “justice” is significant and one reason it is significant is that “each person possesses an inviolability founded on justice.”59 As we see things, making room for a prerogative is one way of giving force to this powerful idea and the implication of this is not just that we must make room for inequality, but that these inequalities are sometimes licensed in the name of justice. This, however, is a conclu- sion that Cohen is hesitant to draw. There is one further problem for the prospects of Cohen’s ethical solu- tion that bears mention. Whatever one thinks of Cohen’s objection to pros- titution, it does suggest an important question, namely whether the merely physical “yielding” of the Young Man can truly satisfy the Old Woman in the right way. Although we earlier assumed for the sake of argument that the Old Woman’s preferences accurately tracked her welfare, there are good reasons for believing that the Young Man’s yielding to her would not in the end satisfy her. For an extremely lonely person, any human contact 58 Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality, p. 304. 59 Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality, p. 305. Here Cohen quotes Rawls approvingly, the idea being that appeals to justice give strength to individuals’ claims that they would otherwise lack. J. Thrasher and K. Hankins / Journal of Moral Philosophy (2013) 22 DOI 10.1163/17455243-4681035 is often welcomed. Being with the Young Man might, very well then, be able to eliminate some of the negative effects of isolation and alleviate some of the Old Women’s loneliness. She would no doubt be aware, how- ever, that the Young Man did not love her or desire to be with her in any way except insofar as his sense of equality required it. Peter Railton, in a similar context, describes this type of situation as a kind of alienation.60 In his example, a husband performs all the duties that a loving husband would perform, but his reasons for acting the way that he does is his devotion to morality, not, strictly speaking, his dedication to his wife. As Railton suggests, “something seems wrong”—after all, one doesn’t only want to be treated as a means of discharging moral duties or as a means of increasing the amount of well-being in the world.61 Imagine a son telling his mother upon visiting her at her home that he is visiting her because she is old and lonely and morality requires that the lonely be vis- ited periodically. Or imagine a wife embracing her husband, not because she has any particular affection for him but rather because she knows that her husband’s well-being will improve if he is embraced. Surely, both of these situations, along with our example borrowed from Aristophanes seem perverse in the same way that Cohen thinks prostitution is perverse. Love and affection are given freely for reasons of love and affection, not for reasons of morality or equality. The problem, we have argued, is that however strong the Young Man’s commitment to equality is, that alone will not allow him to satisfy the demands of justice. In the trilemma case, Cohen argues that someone with an egalitarian ethos acts without coercion when they act in accordance with equality and so, freedom can be consistent with equality. The egalitar- ian ethos alone, however, will not achieve equality in the Aristophanes case because acting from an egalitarian ethos provides the wrong kind of reason to the Young Man. The Old Woman needs the Young Man to love or desire her for the right reasons, and an egalitarian ethos does not provide those reasons to the Young Man, no matter how committed he is to it. Reasons of equality are dictated by how closely they track distributive desiderata. Reasons of love, on the other hand, come from the deeply held desires that are directed at the object of love. To truly achieve equality in our example, we would need to change the desires of the Young Man, but 60 Peter Railton, ‘Alienation, Consequentialism, and the Demands of Morality,’ Philosophy and Public Affairs, 13 (1984), pp. 134–171, at pp. 135–137. 61 Railton, ‘Alienation, Consequentialism, and the Demands of Morality’, pp. 134–171, at p. 136. J. Thrasher and K. Hankins / Journal of Moral Philosophy (2013) DOI 10.1163/17455243-4681035 23 this might not be possible. Further, even if it were possible, as our discus- sion of personal prerogatives has suggested, it may not be desirable for, as Cohen himself affirms, justice to not be all encompassing in this way. We should not be slaves to social justice. Cohen may be right that justice does not license the degree of inequality that many others have supposed. He may also be right that justice requires us to adopt an egalitarian ethos. Our suggestion here is simply that even if we grant Cohen’s claim that adopting an egalitarian ethos may help to alle- viate the tension between co-realizing the values of freedom, equality, and Pareto, we need to do more to fully dissolve that tension. It is not only minds that need to be changed, but also hearts, and even that may not be enough. Finally, although we have levied a series of objections against Cohen’s proposed solution to the trilemma argument, it is worth noting that the failure of Cohen’s Ethical Solution does not present the sort of problem that Cohen supposes. While we might still lament inequality, if justice is about more than just equality, licensing inequalities in the name of justice need not be self-effacing. On the contrary, sometimes constraining the reach of justice serves as a way of respecting the separate worth and importance of individual lives.62 62 The authors would like to thank Jerry Gaus, Bill Glod, Guido Pincione, David Schmidtz, Kevin Vallier, Steven Wall, and an anonymous reviewer for helpful comments on earlier drafts. Special thanks to the participants in a seminar on egalitarianism at the University of Arizona, especially to Tom Christiano who organized and ran the seminar. His early interest in the project was extremely important. When Justice Demands Inequality work_bjvudurxpbayfkeldq42wj6z2m ---- Neutrality, nature, and intergenerational justice Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=fenp20 Environmental Politics ISSN: (Print) (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/fenp20 Neutrality, nature, and intergenerational justice Britta Clark To cite this article: Britta Clark (2020): Neutrality, nature, and intergenerational justice, Environmental Politics, DOI: 10.1080/09644016.2020.1779564 To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/09644016.2020.1779564 Published online: 16 Jun 2020. Submit your article to this journal Article views: 16 View related articles View Crossmark data https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=fenp20 https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/fenp20 https://www.tandfonline.com/action/showCitFormats?doi=10.1080/09644016.2020.1779564 https://doi.org/10.1080/09644016.2020.1779564 https://www.tandfonline.com/action/authorSubmission?journalCode=fenp20&show=instructions https://www.tandfonline.com/action/authorSubmission?journalCode=fenp20&show=instructions https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/mlt/10.1080/09644016.2020.1779564 https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/mlt/10.1080/09644016.2020.1779564 http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1080/09644016.2020.1779564&domain=pdf&date_stamp=2020-06-16 http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1080/09644016.2020.1779564&domain=pdf&date_stamp=2020-06-16 Neutrality, nature, and intergenerational justice Britta Clark Department of Philosophy, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA, USA ABSTRACT Suppose the present generation leaves future ones with a world depleted of all the natural resources required for many valuable human pursuits. Has the present generation acted unjustly? According to contemporary theories of liberal egalitarian intragenerational and intergenerational justice, the answer, it appears, is no. The explanation for this verdict lies in the liberal commitment to remaining neutral between different ways of life: many value-laden environ- mental sites and species are not an all-purpose means to any reasonable human end and so their existence is not directly relevant in an assessment of whether justice obtains. Against this view, I argue that a commitment to neutrality and its underlying justification – the idea that individuals should be equipped to live lives of their own design – in fact supports the opposite conclusion. If justice requires that citizens can pursue whatever way of life they do or might value, then it will also demand the continued existence of the natural resources necessary for those pursuits. KEYWORDS Intergenerational justice; neutrality; John Rawls; future generations; environmental justice Introduction Donald Trump has enacted more sweeping rollbacks of environmental regulation than any president in history. To take a few examples, in 2017 Trump signed bills to reduce the size of Bears Ears National Monument by 85% and the Grand-Staircase Escalante National Monument by 51% (Nordhaus 2018a). In that same year, he withdrew a rule requiring the maintenance of natural resources affected by federal projects and opened the Arctic National Wildlife Refuge to oil and natural gas development (Popovich et al. 2019). Put only somewhat apocalyptically, Trump’s envir- onmental agenda might just leave future people a barren and desolate world void of many of the natural places and species we value now. It is obvious to many that there is something deplorable about bequeath- ing this kind of earth to our children. Former President Obama, for instance, has lamented that ‘rising temperatures could mean no more glaciers in Glacier National Park, no more Joshua trees in Joshua Tree National CONTACT Britta Clark brittaclark@g.harvard.edu ENVIRONMENTAL POLITICS https://doi.org/10.1080/09644016.2020.1779564 © 2020 Informa UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis Group http://www.tandfonline.com https://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1080/09644016.2020.1779564&domain=pdf&date_stamp=2020-06-16 Park . . . that’s not the America I want to pass on to the next generation’ (Obama 2016). And philosophers often seem to agree. Brian Barry has declared that though future people ‘might learn to find satisfaction in totally artificial landscapes, walking on the astroturf amid the plastic trees while the electronic birds sing overhead . . . we cannot but believe that something horrible would have happened to human beings if they did not miss real grass, trees, and birds’ (Barry 1997, p. 50). Call the world Barry imagines – an earth depleted of what we now call ‘nature’1 – the ‘Horrible World’. But what, exactly, is so horrible about it? This is a big question, and below I will explore one aspect of it. I want to know whether dominant theories of liberal equality register the Horrible World as unjust. For today, I set aside the thought that the Horrible World is aesthetically bad or that the places destroyed were intrinsically valuable.2 To make some progress on this still ambitious inquiry, I proceed in three main sections. In the next section, I examine prominent theories of liberal justice between contemporaries, in particular the work of John Rawls. I argue that the liberal commitment to remaining neutral between conceptions of the good makes these theories unable to diagnose any injustice in the Horrible World. In the subsequent section, I turn to less well trodden territory and argue that Rawls’ view of intergenerational justice, as well as a recent pro- posal drawing on his work, likewise fail to reflect the Horrible World complaint. What, then, are we to make of any lingering suspicion that it is unjust to leave future people the Horrible World? In the final section I argue that neutrality does not in fact warrant the exclusion of natural resources from what future people are owed. In fact, the motivating thought behind neu- trality – that individuals should be equipped to lead lives of their own design – supports the claim that the present generation is obligated to preserve natural resources when those resources are required for the very possibility of a particular pursuit. And, though my argument is first pre- sented in terms of intergenerational justice, it turns out that the preservation of such spaces is also owed to presently coexisting people. I conclude, how- ever, by suggesting some reasons why, when it comes to long-term environ- mental damage, the distinction between intra and intergenerational justice remains salient. To start, let me explain three features of the Horrible World that will shape my discussion: • In the Horrible World, the environmental goods required for many of the projects and ways of life of presently living people no longer exist. I will assume for now that the existence of such environmental goods is indeed necessary for many valuable human pursuits: from recreational pastimes to indigenous spiritual practices to the particular ways of life of small island nations, many undertakings undeniably rely on the existence of lakes, beaches, rivers, and 2 B. CLARK plant and animal species. I am concerned below with both token features of the natural world – Bears Ears National Monument – and more general aspects of the environment such as ‘rivers.’ Following recent sustainability literature, I will often call these environmental goods Sociocultural Natural Capital, or SCNC.3 • In the Horrible World, humans have developed technology that allows them to satisfy, without the use of SCNC, all their basic biological needs. • In the Horrible World, citizens live under otherwise just institutions and have an adequate set of life options to choose from. You might imagine, for instance, that environmental destruction has made other opportunities and ways of life possible. Noting these three qualities of the Horrible World helps make my central question more precise. I am not asking whether future people have been treated unjustly if they are left an environment that provides them with meager life opportunities, or one so depleted that it would make sense to say that their rights have been violated.4 Rather, I want to know whether there is anything unjust about revoking from future people the option for them to participate in currently valuable human pursuits involving the natural world.5 SCNC and intragenerational justice I have cast this question and much of my forthcoming discussion in terms of intergenerational justice, which I am understanding here as justice between individuals that never coexist. And though we are often enjoined to preserve the environment ‘for future generations,’ it would be premature, I think, to continue to investigate the role of SCNC in our nascent theorizing of intergenerational justice without first examining more familiar intragenera- tional proposals. In this section, then, I ask the following: can a standard intragenerational Rawlsian view diagnose any injustice in the Horrible World? I will argue, with others who have come before me, that the answer is no.6 To make my case, we’ll have to step back and consider where SCNC best fits into Rawls’ theory. Rawls himself does not substantively address this. A natural place to look, though, is in Rawls’ answer to what has come to be known as the question of the ‘metric’ of justice. This metric is a description of the features of a representative individual’s situation that are to be assessed to determine whether persons like them have been treated justly. In other words, what, exactly, should we measure to compare different people’s circumstances? ENVIRONMENTAL POLITICS 3 Rawls’ answer to the metric question is influenced by his commitment to allowing individuals to form, revise, and pursue their conception of the good without external influence. This means that the relevant measure of distri- butive shares cannot be based on the satisfaction of an individual’s informed preferences or whether they have at their disposal the goods required for the most important human projects. For Rawls, determining if a person has been treated justly does not depend on whether they have what they actually want or even what they should want. Instead, justice requires that each individual have the resources to autonomously design their life, forming an ever- revisable view about what they want and pursuing whatever that happens to be on equal terms with others. This thought leads Rawls and other liberals to adopt a ‘neutral’ or ‘non- perfectionist’ answer to the metric question. To avoid privileging certain conceptions of the good, thereby constraining some individuals’ ability to pursue whatever projects they deem valuable, the measure of distributive shares must be some set of resources that are useful towards any justice- respecting pursuit. With this in mind, Rawls looks to specify a set of neutral primary goods that ‘normally have use whatever a person’s rational plan in life’ (Rawls 1971, p. 62). ‘Income and wealth,’ and ‘the social bases of self- respect,’ for instance, are paradigmatically neutral primary goods. If instead the metric of justice was some non-universally valuable good – basketballs, let’s say – we would be treating those that do not value basketball as having less of a claim to live a life of their own design. Importantly, though, Rawls does not aspire for the fair distribution of primary goods to have neutral consequences with regard to which ways of life fare best in a society (Rawls 1988, p. 260). Rather, the central thought is this: the metric of justice should be framed not in terms of the final goods that people value, but in terms of the principal means to pursue whatever it is that they do or might value. With this sketch of Rawls’ view in hand, it is clear that the neutrality constraint excludes SCNC from the metric of justice. Despite some envir- onmentalists’ intuitions to the contrary, rivers, lakes, and species are not the kinds of things that everyone has reason to want whatever else they want; SCNC is not an all-purpose means to the realization of one’s plan in life. In fact, many important projects may be best pursued by developing and despoiling such resources. On Rawls’ articulation of the metric of justice, though a just distribution of primary goods will make environmental pur- suits possible, we need not examine SCNC itself to determine if justice obtains. Rawls affirms this conclusion, noting that ‘the status of the natural world and our proper relation to it is not a constitutional essential or a basic question of justice’ (Rawls 1971, p. 246). This approach to SCNC is shared by other liberals. Ronald Dworkin, for instance, leaves SCNC outside the metric of justice for similar reasons of neutrality. He describes a potential dispute between developers looking to 4 B. CLARK construct a ‘useful dam’ and an environmental group advocating for the preservation of a species of snail darter, ultimately concluding that the debate is a matter of equally valid albeit conflicting preferences (Dworkin 1981, p. 202; cf. Miller 1999, p. 160). The debate should be resolved via some democratic mechanism, but whether the snail darter continues to exist is not itself a concern of justice. For these prominent theorists, it looks like including SCNC in the metric of justice would illegitimately import a specific conception of the good into a neutral space, equivalent to claiming that each is owed, as a matter of justice, a share of basketballs. I am sympathetic to this impulse: I do not wish for my argument to turn on the idea that the existence of SCNC is the kind of thing that individuals want regardless of what else they want, or the perfec- tionist claim that pursuits involving nature are superior. Indeed, even if this latter claim were true it would not entail that SCNC ought to be included in the metric of justice. Again, it is a crucial feature of the liberal view that what is most important is not that people take up activities conducive to flourish- ing, but that they are provided the resources to lead lives ‘from the inside’ (Kymlicka 2002, p. 216). What should be clear at this point is that on familiar liberal views, environmental protection is downstream from justice. As Rawls emphasizes, decisions regarding the preservation of SCNC are to be governed by ‘the benefit principle and not the principles of justice’ (1971, p. 250). But this might not be cause for concern: many theorists seem optimistic that a fair distribution of some all-purpose metric will enable citizens to effectively prevent something like the Horrible World. Perhaps, even, though SCNC is not itself a matter of justice, neutral state support can promote environ- mental preservation. Dworkin, for instance, notes that institutional incen- tives may be necessary in order to maintain establishments such as National Parks (Dworkin 1985, ch., p. 11), and Rawls similarly suggests that SCNC is a public good potentially warranting state funding (1971, p. 250). Of course, these provisions remain decidedly neutral – the liberal state cannot impose the protection of SCNC, and decisions regarding environmental preservation should be voted on ‘unanimously, or at least approximately so,’ (Rawls 1971, p. 250).7 Rawls and Dworkin do not discuss natural resources in much more depth elsewhere, and seem confident that the sort of neutral state support outlined above will be enough to preclude the Horrible World. I think this is unduly optimistic. To see this, consider a reasonably just society with a 100-acre forest, a forest that is required for many other important pursuits. What claims do present day people have with respect to this resource on the liberal view just outlined? Few are in support of the thought – pejoratively termed ‘absurdly strong sustainability’8 – that justice requires the forest to remain unchanged over time. Not every instance of environmental modification can plausibly be considered an injustice against ENVIRONMENTAL POLITICS 5 those for whom the resource is valuable. What the forest-valuers are owed on the Rawlsian account is the basic liberties ensuring that their preferences are registered in decisions regarding the forest and a fair share of primary goods to pursue a life involving it if they so choose. The just society, then, will permit some development and degradation of the forest. Even if the state offers neutral tax incentives for cultural institu- tions, there is no guarantee that citizens will choose to support environ- mental protection in light of other options, nor does it seem plausible that they will make large enough contributions to prevent every instance of environmental damage. Suppose, then, that in a super-majority or even unanimous vote like the one imagined by Rawls, the community agrees to cut down an acre of the forest for a basketball factory. The forest is now 99 acres. The next year, citizens vote to install a museum. The forest is now 98 acres. And so on. Eventually, the forest is 50 acres. We have yet to see an instance of injustice. But here is the problem: putatively just environmental modification is strikingly unidirectional. While each instance of benign damage is unlikely to be reversed, every instance of environmental preservation, conservation, or improvement remains subject to contestation. Once the forest is 50 acres, it will likely not return to its former size. It’s hard to see the basketball factory, a source of employment and income, being torn down to return the land to forest. In contrast, the forest-valuers who work to preserve it are always vulnerable to the demands of the basketball-valuers, the museum-valuers, and so on. As Elizabeth Ellis (2016) puts the problem, when it comes to environmental damage, ‘each win for the development side is permanent, while each win for the conservation side is temporary’ (507). In short, the idea here – one commonly evoked in environmental policy and sustainability discussions – is that many environmental damages are irreversible, at least over the timespan of a human life.9 The proposition that some environmental damages are irreversible will be important in what follows. And though I cannot offer a full defense of this contested claim here, let me outline two points in support. First, some instances of environmental modification are, at least at present, technologi- cally irreversible. Species extinction, the sea level rise that threatens historic beaches, soil erosion and desertification, ocean acidification, and the death of coral reefs are just the beginning of a lengthy list of changes that are unlikely to be reversible. Second, psychological factors contribute to the irreversibility of environmental decline. As individuals determine whether they are willing to pay for the preservation of SCNC, they will take as a baseline the condi- tions they have themselves encountered (Horowitz 2002, p. 252). In our forest example, for instance, those that only experience the forest at the diminished dimension of 50 acres will take 50 acres as their standard for environmental quality, and further as loss-averse creatures they will be far 6 B. CLARK more concerned with preventing additional losses to the size of the forest than they will be with a comparable improvement or return to past condi- tions (Kahneman and Tversky 1979). Moreover, even with increased defor- estation they will adapt to changing conditions and be unlikely to notice a decline in wellbeing (Raudsepp-Hearne et al. 2010). It seems plausible then, that these technological and psychological factors render some damages to SCNC irreversible. You would, of course, be right to notice that the claim of irreversibility seems to depend on a further claim of irreplaceability or incommensurability (Sunstein 2008, p. 15–17). That is, what makes irreversible damage to SCNC meaningfully irreversible is the fact that that SCNC has no substitutes. Though substitutability has generated extensive discussion, we can set much of it aside here: the debate tends to turn on whether human-made substitutes can generate the same amount of wellbeing as natural capital like SCNC. All that matters for my purposes, though, is that SCNC is a non-substitutable requirement for the very possi- bility of particular human pursuits. Though I will return to this thought, I will continue to assume for now that this is true. Some ways of life are impossible without the existence of particular resources; this is true regard- less of the amount of wellbeing provided by any alternative. What I hope to have established above is that a basic Rawlsian picture can neither directly include SCNC in the metric of justice nor preclude the Horrible World with additional institutional projections. Further, note that the generation that inherits that Horrible World will not have a legitimate claim to live in a world like ours. Though they are born into depleted circumstances, they can still have all their basic liberties protected, and primary goods can still be justly distributed. And nowhere does Rawls or Dworkin state, nor does it seem plausible, that persons have a claim to be able to pursue any imaginable human project. The future people in the Horrible World on the views just explored have no more of a claim to be able to live lives as snail darter enthusiasts or birders than we presently have a claim to live our lives as Samurai Warriors.10 Thus far, though, I’ve focused on justice between coexisting people. Given the long-term nature of environmental harms, it makes sense that this might not be the right place to look. Intuitively, if there is an injustice in the Horrible World, it is not between the individuals that inherit it, but between currently living people and our Horrible World descendants. Accordingly, I now turn to the less frequented conceptual territory of intergenerational justice. SCNC and intergenerational justice Do liberal theories of intergenerational justice provide additional conceptual resources that might impugn the Horrible World? It’s not entirely clear. ENVIRONMENTAL POLITICS 7 Rawls spent only a few pages discussing justice between non-contemporaries, and in general theories of intergenerational justice are less developed than their intragenerational counterparts. In this section I will argue that a plausible reading of Rawls’ intergenerational theory of just savings does not register the Horrible World as an injustice. Nor can more thorough proposals that – in the spirit of Rawls – conceive of intergenerational justice in terms of the all-purpose resource of ‘ecological space.’ Take note at the outset that I will be assuming that it is possible to stand in relations of justice with future people. Admittedly this assumption may be premature: attempts to defend our obligations to future people run into significant difficulties.11 But I take for granted that there is some currency of advantage that we can use to diagnose – by comparing the life prospects of people that never coexist – cases of distinctively intergenerational injustice. What, then, is the appropriate intergenerational metric? On Rawls’ view, intergenerational justice does not require that non-overlapping individuals holds a particular share of primary goods relative to each other; he rejects an intergenerational difference principle that would allow only those interge- nerational inequalities in primary goods that would benefit those in the worst-off generation (Rawls 1971, p. 255–58, Wall 2003, p. 79). Rather, once just intragenerational institutions are set up, our intergenerational duties are exhausted by the requirement to save sufficient material capital such that future people can maintain those just institutions – the so-called just savings principle (Rawls 1971, p. 284–88).12 Just savings is not particularly demanding. Intergenerational injustice only obtains if those in an earlier generation act such that later generations are no longer able to protect the basic liberties of its citizens, or if the economic institutions that regulate unjustifiable inequalities no longer func- tion. Once more, it’s hard to see how this sketch of Rawls’ intergenerational metric has the conceptual resources to mark any injustice in the Horrible World. Recall that though the Horrible World is horrible by the standards of some of today’s citizens, the Horrible World still has well-functioning and intragenerationally just – by Rawls’ standards – institutions. The citizens of the Horrible World can still pursue whatever versions of the good life have been made available via the destruction of the natural world. Though Rawls himself did not articulate a comprehensive theory of intergenerational justice, some theorists have proposed Rawlsian-inspired views that look to capture the intergenerational character of environmental concerns. Steve Vanderheiden (2009) and Tim Hayward (2006), for instance, rightly observe that, unlike Rawlsian primary goods, many natural resources are finite – or at least there is a finite amount that we can consume without disastrous consequences. Vanderheiden and Hayward call these zero-sum resources ‘ecological space,’ which they define loosely as ‘the amount of biologically productive land and water area required to produce the 8 B. CLARK resources consumed and to assimilate the wastes generated using prevailing technology’ (Hayward 2006, p. 359). The central thought is that intergenera- tional justice should register the fact that one generation’s use of ecological space entails the decline of another’s. Roughly, they propose that ‘each human being should be allocated a share of ecological space’ (Page 2007, p. 460), and that the project of intergenerational justice is incomplete with- out a principle for the intertemporal distribution of uniquely finite natural resources. The idea that ecological space is at least part of the evaluative standard of intergenerational justice shares the liberal commitment to neutrality. Ecological space is taken as a universally valuable resource the fair distribu- tion of which will secure even future people’s capacity to autonomously form and revise their conception of the good. As Vanderheiden puts it, the ‘allocation of ecological space defines the sphere in which persons can make the kind of autonomous choices that liberalism celebrates, within the constraints that it recognizes’ (259). However, despite the important recog- nition of zero-sum resources, ecological space does not capture any injustice in the Horrible World. Conceiving of environmental goods under the single heading of ‘ecological space’ obscures distinctions between the different roles played by such goods, failing to provide theoretical support for the thought that intergenerational justice might require that some specific resources – SCNC – should not be distributed for consumption. Moreover, the concern of theorists of ecological space is centered upon the role of such resources in the provision of basic needs – needs which are provided for in the Horrible World. Though there is more to explore here, the crucial point is this: one generation might use up only its fair share of ‘ecological’ space, while still destroying SCNC. Justice of ecological space is consistent with the Horrible World. So it looks like these two metrics of intergenerational justice do not diagnose the Horrible World as unjust. Where are we to go from here? A first option is to say that the Horrible World intuition is mistaken; the liberal environmentalist must admit that environmental preservation is not a matter of justice. A second option is to argue the SCNC should be included in our theories of intragenerational justice, a route taken up by many green political theorists and philosophers.13 However, these theorists tend not to finely distinguish between SCNC in its role supporting the possibility of certain human projects, and aspects of the environment – clean air and water, a habitable climate – which are more plausibly seen as all-purpose means to one’s ends (e.g., Caney 2010). On this approach, if SCNC is preserved, it seems like a happy consequence of a plausible obligation to maintain other more basic environmental services. Where a distinction is indeed drawn, decisions regarding non-universally valuable environmental goods are left to democratic mechanisms or deliberative procedures that ENVIRONMENTAL POLITICS 9 register only existing people’s preferences (e.g. Miller 1999). Even Marcel Wissenburg, who argues that ‘no goods shall be destroyed unless unavoid- able and unless they are replaced by perfectly identical goods’ (1999, p. 123) leaves a determination of what counts as ‘unavoidable’ to be a matter of existing individual tastes, and explicitly accepts that a ‘global Manhattan without the park,’ in which all SCNC is destroyed, does not necessarily constitute an injustice. Further, though some, including Brian Barry (1997) maintain that future people should be left with a set of ‘adequate options’ from which to design their lives, it is often conceded that it is difficult to offer a principled distinction between the options available in the Horrible World and the options we enjoy today. In sum, the claim that there is some injustice in bequeathing the Horrible World to our successors has not yet enjoyed a reasoned defense. Neutrality and SCNC In this final section, I try to make some progress by approaching the Horrible World intuition from the perspective of intergenerational justice. To do this, I will first defend an idea I’ve thus far assumed: certain human projects can be made impossible to pursue if the resources required for those projects are irreversibly destroyed. If this is right, then a commitment to remaining neutral between different conceptions of the good no longer justifies the exclusion of such resources from the metric of intergenera- tional justice. In fact, the neutralist should endorse the opposite conclusion. If the present generation is obligated to ensure that it is possible for future people to pursue any reasonable conception of the good, then the present generation is also obligated to ensure the continued existence of the resources required for such conceptions. However, though my proposal is most vivid in its intergenerational form, it turns out that the same argu- ment applies to the intragenerational case as well. Does this mean that the distinction is trivial? I will close this section by suggesting some reasons to think that it is not. First, let me review and make more precise exactly the challenge posed to liberals hoping to argue that bequeathing the Horrible World is an inter- generational injustice. We observed above that Rawlsian just savings and ecological space both excluded from the purview of justice resources that are not an all-purpose means to human ends and as a result could not diagnose any injustice in the Horrible World. Theorists seemed optimistic that a fair provision of neutral primary goods will prevent much objectionable irrever- sible environmental damage: citizens will be able to register their preferences for a world with SCNC, and if needed neutral state support can incentivize conservation alongside other public goods. This optimism was perhaps appropriate in earlier times when humankind’s influence was not drastic 10 B. CLARK enough to occasion irreversible environmental damage, but today, I argued, it is unfounded. Yet, an optimism that valuable opportunities will persist is also an impor- tant feature of the liberal view. Liberals celebrate that in the free marketplace of ideas facilitated by the basic liberties, some ways of life will be replaced with more valuable projects and activities. As Mill puts it, ‘the worth of different modes of life should be proved practically’ (Mill 1982, p. 53). The human pursuits that are feasible in a given historical moment are always and should always be in flux, lest people be confined to existing practices in objectionable ways. Conceptions of the good that are most popular in a society should evolve, and as noted a commitment to allowing individuals to lead lives of their own design does not require that each of the innumer- able possible human pursuits is always a popular or practical option. So if leaving the Horrible World is an injustice, it cannot be because those that live in it have been denied a maximally expansive set of options from which to choose. Of course, liberals can’t make the perfectionist claim that citizens in the Horrible World are owed SCNC on the basis of the objective superiority of SCNC-involving pursuits, nor, as I’ve emphasized, is it plau- sible that SCNC is an all-purpose means to whatever one’s ends happen to be. Is there any other principled reason to include SCNC in the metric of intergenerational justice? The challenge can be put like this: without recourse to the above arguments, do we have any reason to distinguish between the fact that today it’s not feasible to be a Samurai Warrior and in the Horrible World one cannot pursue projects involving SCNC? We have already seen a potential basis for making this distinction. Dworkin gives us a hint. The liberal, he says, is free to claim that ‘the conquest of unspoiled terrain by the consumer economy is self-fueling and irreversible, and that this process will make a way of life that has been desired and found satisfying in the past unavailable to future generations . . . this way of life will become unknown, so that the process is not neutral amongst competing ideas of the good life, but in fact destructive to the very possibility of some of these. ’ (Dworkin 1985, p. 202). Here, then, is the response to the challenge that I will explore: some human projects can be made impossible to pursue, and others can only be made less feasible. This is because some – but not all – pursuits necessitate the existence of certain physical features of the world. Thus far, I’ve assumed something like this last claim to be true. I will now clarify and defend this assumption. First, notice that some pursuits are by their very nature concerned with engaging with token places that were of value to one’s ancestors and will likely be of value to one’s progeny (Thompson 2009, Scheffler 2013). Existing members of the Zuni tribe, descendants of the inhabitants of the shrunken Bears Ears National Monument, wish to pursue ways of life that involve not simply canyons and mesas generally, but their particular ancestral homeland ENVIRONMENTAL POLITICS 11 (Nordhaus 2018b). If those token places are irreversibly destroyed, then conceptions of the good that are centered around those specific sites become impossible to pursue. It’s hard to imagine what it would look like to engage with one’s ancestral home if one’s ancestral home has been developed into an oil field. The second and more difficult claim to establish is that some pursuits that do not require such intergenerationally valuable token resources can likewise become impossible to pursue in the absence of certain SCNC. But this is plausible: in the Horrible World a litany of recreational, spiritual, and otherwise valuable human undertakings – birding, fishing, swimming, climbing, gardening – do not seem possible to pursue despite the fact that these projects are not concerned with specific token sites. Notice an impor- tant difference between making a pursuit impossible and making a pursuit less feasible or impractical. Though we find an individual who pursues life as a Samurai warrior odd, in a place like the Horrible World the pursuit of projects involving the natural world will be irrational–comparable to a contemporary individual whose conception of the good involves living with dinosaurs (Ott 2004, p. 144). The Samurai-fighting enthusiast will likely have little success, yet she can meaningfully pursue her admittedly strange idea of a good life. The resources required for Samurai-fighting cannot be irreversibly removed from existence, for there are many ways to construct the required swords and shields. The present generation cannot altogether preclude future individuals from pursuing that particular way of life. In contrast, when it comes to SCNC, this does not seem to be the case: it is simply not possible for the citizens of the Horrible World to pursue any activities involving the natural world with any chance of success. At this point you’re likely worried that this last claim is too strong. It’s not really impossible, you might object, to pursue birding in the absence of real birds; you might devote your life to de-extinction technologies or perhaps virtual birds will do the trick. Looking ahead, you might rightly be concerned that my view will end up being overdemanding: surely it is not a concern of justice if wealthy future people cannot ski in the Alps or raft down a pristine river. This is an important objection, and it sheds light on a larger question that I cannot address in full here. To know whether my view has these sorts of demanding implications, we need to know what counts as a ‘pursuit,’ ‘way of life,’ or ‘conception of the good.’ Further, we need an account of when natural resources are indeed necessary for the very possibility of pursuing a way of life. Though I will not investigate these questions here, I suspect that any plausible account will include both intergenerationally valuable token resources as well as some other general types of SCNC. Regardless of how one answers the above questions, I believe I have identified the right kind of distinction between conceptions of the good that require the existence of SCNC and those that do not. The former is 12 B. CLARK distinctive not because such projects are superior or because those resources are all-purpose means to one’s ends, but because projects requiring SCNC can be made not just impractical but impossible to pursue. The final step is to argue that this distinction can be wielded to show that the Horrible World is an injustice. Recall the motivation supporting liberal neutrality. A neutral metric of justice was important because it embodied the idea that justice should not privilege particular ways of life, but rather ensure that individuals can form a revisable conception of what they value as well as pursue whatever that ends up being. But we also saw above that the intergenerational metrics of just savings and ecological space were consistent with allowing some conceptions of the good to become not just impractical, but impossible. That is, these purport- edly neutral metrics of justice did exactly what they were designed to avoid: they dictated in advance the kinds of lives that future humans can possibly lead. Though individuals in the Horrible World can form and revise their values against a background of ample options, some options will be simply unavailable to them. And they won’t be unavailable in the sense that other undertakings have become more popular. Rather, they are impossible because the resources necessary for those pursuits no longer exist. Put otherwise, the threat to many conceptions of the good is only that humans may cease to value them, and they will become unpopular ways of life. But the threat to conceptions of the good requiring SCNC is distinctive: the resources required for these projects can be irreversibly destroyed, mak- ing these projects impossible to pursue. To be sure, many human under- takings will still fade out of fashion, becoming less feasible or desirable for future people. And for the most part this evolution is the product of humans reflecting on and deciding what is valuable, and teaching their children the same. Those children can form and revise their conceptions of the good in spite of this education, choosing if they wish to return to a way of life that was valued in the past, attempting to convince others to join them. In general the resources needed to do this are available to them. But in some cases, those resources can be irreversibly destroyed, rendering those projects not just impractical or unpopular, but impossible. My conclusion, then, is that a commitment to neutrality does not warrant the exclusion of SCNC from the metric of intergenerational justice. This is the deep truth behind Dworkin’s point: we ought not make particular ways of life permanently unavailable if we are genuinely committed to ensuring that future individuals can lead lives of their own design. An intergenerational metric that excludes SCNC prescribes, in a manner in deep tension with liberalism’s commitment to neutrality, the very sorts of lives that future citizens may be able to pursue. The supposed commitment to neutrality in existing theories of intergenerational justice is anything but, for it allows that the only lives future people can live are those that are still possible once we ENVIRONMENTAL POLITICS 13 have lived ours. When individuals in a future generation wonder whether they have been treated justly by us, I propose that part of the standard of assessment is that we have not made particular ways of life impossible for them to pursue. The fact that I have left fairly open what it means to make a conception of the good impossible to pursue means that my argument does not necessarily endorse as demanding of conservation policies as you might have thought. If ways of life are understood as wide and non-descript – like ‘being outside’ – then it will be virtually impossible for the present generation to fail in an obligation to keep this way of life around. In contrast, if ways of life are narrowly specified – ‘skiing on real snow at X resort’ – our present obligation to maintain the possibility of all such options would impose unreasonable demands. I suspect that the right view falls somewhere between these two extremes. At this point, though, it appears the distinction I have been making between intra and intergenerational justice is not doing all that much work, for the very same reasons that supporting the inclusion of SCNC in the metric of intergenerational justice supports the inclusion of SCNC in what is owed to existing people. If the Horrible World were to come to exist tomorrow, with pursuits involving snail darters, forests, and the like replaced by technological substitutes, existing people would find some ways of life impossible. This restriction, like the intergenerational case, is inconsistent with the liberal commitment to providing to each the required resources to go about pursuing whatever it is they happen to value. Those who already hold or come to form a conception of the good requiring the destroyed resources will find their conception of the good not only unpopular, but impossible, as will future people that might one day wish to pursue projects involving SCNC. However, I think we should keep the intra/intergenerational distinction in clear view. If I am right to think that acting justly towards future people requires not irreversibly restricting their ability to meaningfully pursue conceptions of the good, then the present generation has environmental obligations not easily identified solely in terms of what is owed to present people. First, in what has been called the problem of delayed harms, the present generation might act in ways that occasion irreversible damage to SCNC that will only be felt in the future. Currently living people, that is, could continue to pursue valuable projects over the course of their lifetime while at the same time setting in motion processes that will make these same projects impos- sible in the future. Climate change and extinction are particularly obvious examples of this: we are presently acting in ways that may not make some conceptions of the good impossible for ourselves, but will render those same projects impossible for our successors. Think, for instance, of a future 14 B. CLARK individual who forms a conception of the good involving living on the same Fijian island as their ancestors – an island that will soon be underwater due to anthropocentric climate change. The second reason that the distinction between intergenerational and intragenerational justice remains salient in the case of irreversible environ- mental damage relates to the kind of unanimous decision-making mentioned by Rawls. You might think that when it comes to the goods required for particular projects, an existing generation is within its rights to make that good unavailable for themselves. Acknowledging that not all human projects can be pursued at the same time, the present generation could unanimously vote to make some conceptions of the good impossible in order to more effectively pursue other valuable activities. For instance, we might unan- imously agree to stop funding space exploration in favor of building a new basketball court in every county in America. Similarly, you might think that the present generation could permissibly develop public lands through a unanimous vote. But, if the status of SCNC in the metric of a distinctively intergenerational account of justice is kept in mind, this latter option impermissible. While our successors could reverse the decision to focus on the sporting life instead of life on Mars, future generations cannot choose to continue to pursue those ways of life that have been rendered impossible by the imagined development. In short, recognizing that an obligation to ensure that no conception of the good becomes impossible to pursue is an obligation owed to everyone who will ever live and places more stringent demands and constraints on present action than an exclusive focus on obligations to presently existing people. Conclusion The practical upshot of all this is that environmental preservation and conservation can be justified in terms of the familiar obligation to enable all citizens to pursue whatever it is they do or might value. Though the liberal cannot, on neutral grounds, say that these ways of life are more valuable than the opportunities that might replace them, we can say, on neutral grounds, that no project should be made impossible to pursue. Though I do not fill in an account of when exactly a way of life is impossible, I have suggested there are indeed some conceptions of the good that cannot be pursued in the absence of physical features of the world – SCNC. If this is right, then it appears Rawls was wrong to say that ‘there is no more justification for using the state apparatus to compel some citizens to pay for unwanted benefits that others desire than there is to force them to reimburse others for their private expenses’ (1971, p. 250). In fact, the justification is that, without stricter environmental protection, ways of life that have previously been possible will become meaningless and unintelligible pursuits. ENVIRONMENTAL POLITICS 15 The even broader lesson here, I think, is that our our theorizing about intergenerational justice cannot avoid saying something about what sorts of lives future citizens should have the option to lead. It is an inevitable and benign fact about the development of human societies that the preferences and goals of any generation are deeply influenced by what the past genera- tion themselves valued and what sort of natural and built reality was sus- tained for them. Yet, we have an increasing ability to constrain, in unprecedented ways, the sorts of projects our progeny can pursue. If we are to stay true to a commitment to enabling humans to freely and auton- omously pursue whatever kind of life they find valuable, we must seriously consider our increasing capacity to determine what ways of life remain possible. Notes 1. I will remain neutral with regard to the question of what the term ‘nature’ should refer to. For my purposes, the colloquial thought that nature is all those physical features of the earth that are not of primarily human creation should suffice, but see Chapter 2 in Sakar (2012) for a summary of competing views. 2. Many have argued that there are justice-independent reasons to preserve environmental goods because, for instance, they are intrinsically valuable. See Scanlon (1998, p. 183) for a specific example or Brennan and Lo (2016) for a full survey. 3. See Chiesura and Rudolf (2003), and Satz et al. (2013) for examples. 4. See Brandstedt and Bergman (2013) for a thorough treatment of the rights- based approach to climate change. 5. My analysis could well be extended to other objects that are indispensable for presently living people’s projects: works of art, temples, or churches, for instance. Here, I focus on natural objects, but see Young (1989) for a somewhat similar discussion involving works of art. 6. For some who have come to the roughly similar conclusion that Rawlsians cannot easily accommodate environmental concerns, see Sagoff (2007) Miller and Wissenburg’s contributions in Dobson (1999), and Gardiner (2011). 7. See Brighouse (1995) for an argument that neutrality makes it even more difficult than Dworkin might have thought to justify even neutral state support for cultural projects. 8. See Solow (1974). 9. For instance, the famous ‘precautionary principle’ in the 1992 Rio Declaration demands that ‘where there are threats of serious or irreversible damage, lack of full scientific certainty shall not be used as a reason for postponing cost- effective measures to prevent environmental degradation’. 10. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for highlighting this example; it plays a central role in what follows. 11. For instance, I will not address the non-identity problem here. See Gosseries (2008) and Meyer (2016) for summaries of the various conceptual challenges posed by intergenerational relations. 16 B. CLARK 12. In fact, for Rawls intergenerational justice is a two-stage sequence. Before just institutions are set up, present individuals have an obligation to save to create them (1971, p. 255–258). I will focus on the second stage. 13. For a sampling, see the essays in Dobson (1999). Acknowledgments Many thanks to Elizabeth Ellis, Michael Lebuffe, Jacinta Ruru, and others at the University of Otago for their comments on the initial versions of this manuscript. I am indebted to the United States Fulbright Graduate Student Program for their generous support of a year of research in New Zealand, an experience that inspired this project. Later drafts benefited immensely from the incisive feedback of Lucas Stanczyk, Emilio Mora, Gina Schouten, and many fellow University of Otago and Harvard University graduate students. Thorough observations from three anon- ymous referees were also greatly appreciated. Disclosure statement No potential conflict of interest was reported by the author(s). Funding This work was supported by the Fulbright New Zealand. References Barry, B., 1997. Sustainability and intergenerational justice. Theoria, 44 (89), 43–64. doi:10.3167/004058197783593443 Brandstedt, E. and Bergman, A.K., 2013. Climate rights: feasible or not? Environmental Politics, 22(3), 394–409. doi:10.1080/09644016.2013.775723 Brennan, A. and Lo, Y., 2016. Environmental ethics. In: E.N. Zalta, ed. The Stanford Encyclopedia of philosophy. Stanford: The Metaphysics Research Lab. Brighouse, H., 1995. Neutrality, publicity, and state funding of the arts. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 35–63. 24 1 doi:10.1111/j.1088-4963.1995.tb00021.x Caney, S., 2010. Climate change, human rights, and moral thresholds. In: S.M. Gardiner, ed. Climate ethics: essential readings. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 163–177. Chiesura, A., and Rudolf D., 2003. Critical natural capital: a socio-cultural perspective. Ecological Economics, 44.2–3, 219–231. doi:10.1016/S0921-8009(02) 00275-6 Dobson, A., 1999. Fairness and futurity: essays on environmental sustainability and social justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Dworkin, R., 1981. What is equality? Part 1: equality of welfare. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 10, 185–246. Dworkin, R., 1985. A matter of principle. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Ellis, E., 2016. Democracy as constraint and possibility for environmental action. In: T. Gabrielson, C. Hall, J.M Meyer, and D. Schlosberg, eds. The Oxford handbook of environmental political theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 505–19. ENVIRONMENTAL POLITICS 17 https://doi.org/10.3167/004058197783593443 https://doi.org/10.1080/09644016.2013.775723 https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1088-4963.1995.tb00021.x https://doi.org/10.1016/S0921-8009(02)00275-6 https://doi.org/10.1016/S0921-8009(02)00275-6 Gardiner, S.M., 2011. Rawls and climate change: does Rawlsian political philosophy pass the global test? Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy, 14 (2), 125–151. doi:10.1080/13698230.2011.529705 Gosseries, A., 2008. Theories of intergenerational justice: a synopsis. S.A.P.I.EN.S. Surveys and Perspectives Integrating Environment and Society, 1 (1), 39–49 doi:10.5194/sapiens-1-39-2008 Hayward, T., 2006. Global justice and the distribution of natural resources. Political Studies, 54 (2), 349–369. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9248.2006.00606.x Horowitz, J.K., 2002. Preferences in the future. Environmental and Resource Economics, 21(3), 241–258. doi:10.1023/A:1014592629514 Kahneman, D. and Tversky, A., 1979. Prospect theory: an analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 47 (2), 263–292. doi:10.2307/1914185 Kymlicka, W., 2002. Contemporary political philosophy: an introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Meyer, L., 2016. Intergenerational justice. In: E.N. Zalta, ed. The Stanford Encyclopedia of philosophy. Stanford: The Metaphysics Research Lab. Mill, J.S., 1982. On liberty. Harmondsworth: Penguin. Miller, D., 1999. Social justice and environmental goods. In: A. Dobson, ed. Fairness and futurity: essays on environmental sustainability and social justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 151–172. Nordhaus, H., 2018a. What Trump’s shrinking of national monuments actually means. In: National geographic, February 2nd. https://www.nationalgeographic. com/news/2017/12/trump-shrinks-bearsears-grand-staircase-escalante-national- monuments/ Nordhaus, H., 2018b. What the bears ears monument means to a native American. In: National geographic, October 18th. https://www.nationalgeographic.com/envir- onment/2018/10/bears-earsmonument-native-americans-photography/ Obama, B., 2016. Remarks by the president at sentinel bridge. In: National archives and records administration. National Archives and Records Administration. Ott, K., 2004. Essential components of future ethics. In: R. Döring and M. Rühs, eds. Ökonomische Rationalität und praktische Vernunft, Würzburg. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann, 83–108. Page, E.A., 2007. Intergenerational justice of what: welfare, resources or capabilities? Environmental Politics, 16 (3), 453–469. doi:10.1080/09644010701251698 Popovich, N., et al., 2019. 83 environmental rules being rolled back under Trump. The New York Times. Raudsepp-Hearne, C., et al., 2010. Untangling the environmentalist’s paradox: why is human well-being increasing as ecosystem services degrade? BioScience, 60 (8), 576–589. doi:10.1525/bio.2010.60.8.4 Rawls, J., 1971. A theory of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Rawls, J., 1988. The priority of right and ideas of the good. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 17, 251–276. Sagoff, M., 2007. The economy of the earth: philosophy, law, and the environment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Sarkar, S., 2012. Environmental philosophy: from theory to practice. Hoboken: John Wiley & Sons. Satz, D., et al., 2013. The challenges of incorporating cultural ecosystem services into environmental assessment. Ambio, 42 (6), 675–684. doi:10.1007/s13280-013-0386-6 Scanlon, T., 1998. What we owe to each other. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Scheffler, S., 2013. Death and the Afterlife. New York: Oxford University Press. 18 B. CLARK https://doi.org/10.1080/13698230.2011.529705 https://doi.org/10.5194/sapiens-1-39-2008 https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.2006.00606.x https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1014592629514 https://doi.org/10.2307/1914185 https://doi.org/10.1080/09644010701251698 https://doi.org/10.1525/bio.2010.60.8.4 https://doi.org/10.1007/s13280-013-0386-6 Solow, R.M., 1974. Intergenerational equity and exhaustible resources. The Review of Economic Studies, 41, 29–45. doi:10.2307/2296370 Sunstein, C.R., 2008. Two conceptions of irreversible environmental harm. U of Chicago Law & Economics, Olin Working Paper, (407), 08–16. Thompson, J., 2009. Intergenerational justice: rights and responsibilities in an inter- generational polity. New York: Routledge. Vanderheiden, S., 2009. Allocating ecological space. Journal of Social Philosophy, 40 (2), 257–275. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9833.2009.01450.x Wall, S., 2003. Just savings and the difference principle. Philosophical Studies, 116 (1), 79–102. Wissenburg, M., 1999. An extension of the Rawlsian savings principle to liberal theories of justice in general. In: A. Dobson, ed.. Fairness and futurity: essays on environmental sustainability and social justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 173–198. Young, J.O., 1989. Destroying works of art. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 47 (4), 367–373. doi:10.2307/431136 ENVIRONMENTAL POLITICS 19 https://doi.org/10.2307/2296370 https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9833.2009.01450.x https://doi.org/10.2307/431136 Abstract Introduction SCNC and intragenerational justice SCNC and intergenerational justice Neutrality and SCNC Conclusion Notes Acknowledgments Disclosure statement Funding References work_bjwbnyxnoneu7g6b53jbwl5kpm ---- PATRICK TOMLIN* DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE FOR AGGRESSORS (Accepted 27 December 2019) ABSTRACT. The individualist nature of much contemporary just war theory means that we often discuss cases with single attackers. But even if war is best understood in this individualist way, in war combatants often have to make decisions about how to distribute harms among a plurality of aggressors: they must decide whom and how many to harm, and how much to harm them. In this paper, I look at simultaneous multiple aggressor cases in which more than one distribution of harm among aggressors is available. I show how such cases pose deep questions concerning the nature, role, and scope of the necessity principle, and its relationship to both liability and narrow proportionality. I argue that a hitherto unrecognised measure – ‘narrow proportionality shortfall’ – and its dis- tribution is relevant in choosing how to distribute harms across aggressors. I then extend this analysis to show how this may help us with a puzzle concerning sequential attacks. I. INTRODUCTION The literature on the ethics of war and self-defence will often employ cases in which one attacker threatens one victim. There is much that we can learn from such cases. But war involves many people attacking many people, and so there are some questions, including those concerning distributing harms among culpable or responsible threats, that do not arise in these single-aggressor cases. Here I investigate cases involving more than one aggressor, focusing on cases of multiple simultaneous threats in which more than one distribution of harm is available. Our central question is this: How should we distribute harm among aggressors? * I am grateful to the Oxford War Group, the ELAC 2017 conference in Oslo, and Benjamin Matheson in particular, for useful comments and discussion. I am especially grateful to Helen Frowe, Kieran Oberman, Kim Ferzan and an anonymous referee for extensive written comments. Law and Philosophy (2020) 39: 351–379 � The Author(s). This article is an open access publication 2020 https://doi.org/10.1007/s10982-019-09373-3 http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1007/s10982-019-09373-3&domain=pdf The paper is an exploration of this topic. Several different issues will be investigated, and some new ideas floated. What draws these different issues and ideas together is that I try to show how con- sideration of this question about distributing harm among aggressors can raise deeper questions about, and help us to clarify our views concerning, the relationships between some key concepts. Most importantly, since it is usually thought to be the necessity principle’s job to compare our defensive options, this topic poses some important, and under-investigated, questions about the necessity principle. These include important questions about necessity’s rela- tionship to liability and narrow proportionality, and the scope of the necessity principle’s application, which is possibly a lot more expansive than has been traditionally thought. Having explored these issues through simultaneous-aggressor cases, I then show how the positions reached potentially have implications for a puzzle gener- ated by sequential threat cases. The article proceeds as follows. In Section II, I introduce some key concepts. In Section III, I introduce two key claims about lia- bility – that necessity is internal to liability, and that liability is a one- to-one relation. In Section IV, through considering multiple-aggres- sor cases, I seek to show that at least one of these claims is false. Sections V and VI investigate the scope of the necessity principle. Once we accept some seemingly uncontroversial claims about necessity’s role in distributing harms across attackers, it becomes very difficult to cordon off necessity from having radical implica- tions. Section VII concerns the relationship between narrow pro- portionality and necessity. I argue that necessity ought to take account of something I call ‘narrow proportionality shortfall’. This analysis is extended by Section VIII in which I argue that necessity must take account of distributive concerns, including the distribution of narrow proportionality shortfall. Section IX takes some key les- sons from simultaneous-aggressor cases and applies them to a puzzle concerning sequential aggressors. Section X concludes. II. LIABILITY, NARROW PROPORTIONALITY, AND NECESSITY: THE BASIC MODEL There are, broadly speaking, two categories of people we might subject to defensive harm: those who are innocent (at least with P. TOMLIN352 regard to the present situation) and those who are not. There are, of course, many finer distinctions we could make, and there are, of course, disputes about how and where to draw the line. Neverthe- less, the line is an important one – whether we are harming an innocent bystander or a liable party makes a big moral difference. In this paper, I focus on harms to culpable and responsible aggressors: people who pose an unjustified threat, and bear enough responsi- bility for that threat to be considered potentially liable to harm. Three key concepts will be referred to throughout – liability, narrow proportionality, and necessity. The paper is in part an investigation of the relationships between these concepts, particularly in contexts in which we face a plurality of potentially liable aggressors. When someone is responsible for an unjustified threat, they are standardly thought to have forfeited some of their rights against harm. This means that they are potentially liable to some defensive harm. When we are liable to harm, we have no complaint against it, and are not wronged by it. However, as Jonathan Quong puts it, ‘a person is never liable to defensive harm generally; rather, a person can only be liable to some particular proportionate level of defensive harm.’1 Narrow proportionality concerns the proportionality of harms with a liability justification. It sets a maximum limit to the harm that may be done to someone under that justification, and is based on a variety of factors, including the level of harm threatened and the aggressor’s level of responsibility.2 Narrow proportionality contrasts with wide proportionality, which concerns the proportionality of harms done to the innocent with a lesser-evil justification.3 Some people think that, at least in some contexts, when people forfeit their rights they forfeit their rights all the way up to the maximum set by narrow proportionality. For example, Kit Wellman distinguishes between strong and weak rights forfeiture, and en- dorses strong rights forfeiture in the context of punishment.4 According to this view, a criminal may be punished up to the nar- 1 Jonathan Quong, ‘Proportionality, Liability, and Defensive Harm,’ Philosophy & Public Affairs 43 (2015): 144–173, at pp. 144–145. 2 Jeff McMahan, Killing in War (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), pp. 19–29; David Rodin, ‘Justifying Harm,’ Ethics 122 (2011): 74–110. Quong denies that responsibility is a factor (‘Proportion- ality, Liability, and Defensive Harm’). 3 McMahan, Killing in War, pp. 19–29. 4 Christopher Heath Wellman, ‘The Rights Forfeiture Theory of Punishment,’ Ethics 122 (2012): 371–393, at p. 375. DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE FOR AGGRESSORS 353 rowly proportionate maximum, regardless of whether this punish- ment achieves some further good. However, most, perhaps all, philosophers working on self-defence and war believe in a principle of necessity. This means that they do not endorse strong forfeiture (in Wellman’s sense) in those defensive contexts. In their eyes, narrowly proportionate defensive harms can be impermissible, even when they do no harm to anyone but the responsible threat. In order to be permissible, defensive harm must also be necessary as part of the defensive action. The necessity principle applies most clearly in this kind of case: Imagine I can only fend off an attacker with 20 units of harm. This is narrowly pro- portionate, and it is thus permissible. But now imagine that a new option becomes available, and I can also fend off the attacker with only 10 units of harm. In that case, the 20-unit option includes unnecessary harm, and is thus impermissible. Since using the 20-unit option would involve more harm to the same person to achieve the same end, we can say that this is a case of gratuitous harm.5 Necessity and proportionality, as I understand them here, perform two distinct tasks. Options that would require excessive force given the threat faced are ruled out as disproportionate. Proportionality therefore compares our defensive options with allowing the threat to eventuate. Necessity selects from among our proportionate defen- sive options: Options that would require excessive force given our other proportionate defensive options are ruled out as unnecessary. Necessity therefore compares our defensive options with one an- other. The principle of necessity is not only a principle that limits lia- bility-justified harms. It also limits lesser-evil-justified harms. While I will focus on the relationship between liability and necessity here, it is worth remembering that our account of necessity must suitably limit harmful actions under both justifications. While there is widespread agreement on the requirements of necessity in cases of gratuitous harm, like the one above, there are nevertheless philosophical controversies concerning the principle. For example, there are more complex cases in which it is less easy to determine whether necessity applies and what it requires – the necessity principle is potentially a lot more complex than we might 5 I am grateful to Kim Ferzan and an anonymous referee here. P. TOMLIN354 think from cases of gratuitous harm, and, as we shall see, its rela- tionship to liability is also a matter of controversy.6 III. TWO CLAIMS ABOUT LIABILITY In this section I want to outline two claims about liability. In short form, they are as follows: Claim 1: Necessity is internal to liability Claim 2: Liability is a one-to-one relation I’ll explain each in turn. The first claim, that necessity is internal to liability, is essentially the claim that aggressors are wronged by unnecessary harms, since they are not liable to unnecessary harms. Crucially, this means that what harm one is liable to is in part a matter of what harm is necessary. Others believe that necessity is external to liability. That is, aggressors are liable to narrowly proportionate though unnecessary harms, but it is nevertheless impermissible to impose them. Therefore, while the defensive agent who imposes unnecessary harm acts impermissibly, she does not wrong her aggressor, and the unnecessary harm does not give rise to a complaint.7 The second claim is that liability is a ‘one-to-one relation.’ This is a claim that liability is only concerned with the attacker and their attack. For example, Jeff McMahan states that ‘Liability justifications appear to work by ‘‘pairwise comparisons’’ – that is, by considering each choice between harmings [that is, whether the attacker or the victim is harmed] on its own and determining which of the parties the unavoidable harm ought, as a matter of justice, to be imposed. (This is part of the explanation of why narrow proportionality does not take account of numbers).’8 David Rodin claims that ‘Liability is 6 Seth Lazar, ‘Necessity in Self-Defense and War,’ Philosophy & Public Affairs 40 (2012): 3–44; Jeff McMahan, ‘The Limits of Self-Defense’ in Christian Coons and Michael Weber, eds., The Ethics of Self- Defense (New York: Oxford University Press, 2016). 7 For overviews of these issues, see: Helen Frowe, Defensive Killing (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014), ch. 4; Joseph Bowen, ‘Necessity and Liability: On an Honour-Based Justification for Defensive Harming,’ Journal of Practical Ethics 4 (2016): 79–93. 8 Jeff McMahan, ‘Liability, Proportionality, and the Number of Aggressors,’ in Saba Bazargan and Samuel Rickless, eds., The Ethics of War (New York: Oxford University Press, 2017). DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE FOR AGGRESSORS 355 a localized comparison between persons in a situation of con- flict…values outside that relationship are irrelevant.’9 Here, then, is a commonly accepted claim about liability – it is a one-to-one relation. However, consideration of multiple aggressor cases should lead us, I will argue, to either reject this claim or to downgrade its importance. IV. NECESSITY AND LIABILITY Consider this simultaneous threat case: Case 1: Victim is attacked by two unconnected persons simultaneously, who both intend to kill her, and will do so unless she defends herself. Both are equally responsible. Repelling either attack will cause the other attacker to abandon their attack. Attacker 1 can be repelled with 10 units of harm. Attacker 2 can be repelled with 20 units of harm. Both amounts of harm would be narrowly proportionate. Proponents of strong rights-forfeiture would appear to be committed to the idea that it is permissible to harm Attacker 1, Attacker 2, or both. Since both have forfeited their rights, and there is no necessity condition, both are liable to be harmed up to the proportionate maximum. Most will not accept this conclusion. Most will argue that Victim may harm Attacker 1 and only Attacker 1. Why? Because this minimizes harm. Since the instruction to harm Attacker 1 is an instruction to minimize harm from within the proportionate options, it seems to be the necessity condition that requires Victim to harm Attacker 1 and not Attacker 2. This is not a case of gratuitous harm, since the two potential harms are to two different people. It is a case of how to distribute harm between two liable parties. But it seems that necessity nev- ertheless has something to say (and most would accept that it is necessity that applies here – after all, if necessity had nothing to say whenever harms might befall different persons, it would hardly apply at all in the context of war). Yet, if necessity does apply here, this case tells us something very important about necessity and its rela- tionship to liability. Recall that it is often thought that necessity is internal to liability (Claim 1), and that liability is a one-to-one relation (Claim 2). But if it 9 David Rodin, ‘Justifying Harm,’ p. 99. Rodin doesn’t here use the language of one-to-one rela- tionships, but I think it is a plausible way to read this claim, given his other work, especially on bloodless invasions. However, even if Rodin has a wider definition of ‘situation of conflict’ in mind, we will need an account of what is within and what is outside that situation – something which, as I will show, is tricky to provide. P. TOMLIN356 is necessity that tells us that we ought to harm Attacker 1 and not Attacker 2 in Case 1, then at least one of these two claims must be false. We have a trilemma, in that we cannot, I argue, endorse the claim that necessity tells us to harm Attacker 1, and Claim 1, and Claim 2. In Case 1, if our judgment that Attacker 1 ought to be harmed is based upon necessity, that judgment can only be reached by com- paring harms across attackers. The harm to Attacker 2 is unnecessary, and that level of harm is unnecessary due to the option of inflicting less harm on somebody else. Therefore, necessity is not simply about pairwise comparisons. Since necessity is not simply about pairwise comparisons, then if necessity, in part, determines what harm we’re liable to (i.e., if Claim 1 is true) then liability is not simply a one-to- one relation (i.e., Claim 2 is false). If, on the other hand, Claim 2 is true, and liability can only be established by pairwise comparisons between each Attacker and Victim, then Claim 1 must be rejected – necessity is not internal to liability. We could claim that Attackers 1 and 2 form a ‘unit’, and so this is a single attack, not two separate attacks. Therefore, liability is not quite a one-to-one relation, but it is still limited to those involved in the ‘situation of conflict’. In order to claim this, a defender of this view will need to give us an account of how to demark ‘situations of conflict’. But even if they were able to do so, the conjunction of Claims 1 and 2 would still be in trouble. Consider this case: Case 2: Attacker attacks Victim threatening to kill her. Victim can defend herself by killing Attacker, or scratching Bystander. It seems that necessity would require us to harm Bystander. All else equal we might think Victim is required to harm Attacker, or let herself be harmed, over harming Bystander. But all else is not equal here. Either Victim or Attacker will end up dead, or Victim can very mildly harm Bystander. Bystander is clearly not part of the ‘situation of conflict’ (she is, after all, a bystander) and yet necessity seems to be telling us that she must be harmed. So we again see that necessity looks across the various harmful options, singling one out. And again, not all of these harmful options will harm people involved in the attack. If necessity helps to determine liability, we must reject the claim that liability is a one-to-one relationship. If liability is a one-to- one relationship (or involves only those who are part of the situation DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE FOR AGGRESSORS 357 of conflict) we must deny that necessity helps to determine liability. We could keep Claims 1 and 2 by denying that it is necessity that tells us who to harm in Case 1 and Case 2. On this picture, necessity is more limited, focusing simply on what is necessary to stop this attack (or perhaps it is even more limited, and restricted to ruling out gratuitous harm only). We might then reason through Case 1 as follows. The 20-units harm to Attacker 2 is proportionate and nec- essary. The 10-units harm to Attacker 1 is also proportionate and necessary. And so both attackers are liable to those amounts of harm, since necessity and liability both, on this picture, concern this attacker and the threat that they pose. However, we might think, there is some further principle, external to liability, which states that, of the two necessary harms, one is to be chosen over another. This might be a more general ‘minimizing harm’ principle. One thing to note here is that by postulating two separate prin- ciples – necessity, which is internal to liability, and a minimizing harm principle, which adjudicates between harms to which persons are liable – this view proposes what seems to be a radical revision to defensive morality. The job that the minimizing harm principle is supposed to do is one that necessity has standardly been thought to do – i.e., selecting the minimally harmful option from among our proportionate defensive options. Perhaps they are parts of the same principle – in the way that McMahan has carefully and usefully distinguished between narrow and wide proportionality, perhaps there is a difference between narrow and wide necessity. Narrow necessity is internal to liability, while wide necessity adjudicates between harms to which persons are liable (and, perhaps, other harms too). Here is one potentially attractive entailment of this type of ‘split necessity’ view: since both Attacker 1 and Attacker 2 are liable, it allows us to say that if Victim chooses to harm Attacker 1, she acts impermissibly, but she does not wrong Attacker 1. On this view, you wrong someone when you do more harm than is necessary to them to stop their attack, but you do not wrong them when you fail to minimize harm more generally. However, this view, as currently stated, cannot save the con- junction of Claims 1 and 2. To see this, consider Case 1 again. The position explored above relies on each of the two Attackers being P. TOMLIN358 liable to harm. But, according to this new view, neither attacker is, in fact, liable to harm. If necessity is internal to liability, and liability is a one-to-one relation, then we must look only at the threat each At- tacker poses, and whether the harm to him is necessary to prevent it. On this measure, neither harm is narrowly necessary. There is a way to stop Attacker 1 without harming him at all – namely, harming Attacker 2 – and there is a way to stop Attacker 2 without harming him at all – namely, harming Attacker 1. Therefore, to harm either is to harm him more than is necessary. The view could be amended, however, to fix this problem.10 If narrow necessity rules out comparison with options that harm third parties, then both options in Case 1 are narrowly necessary. In considering whether it is narrowly necessary to harm Attacker 1, I cannot appeal to the fact that I could harm Attacker 2, since Attacker 2 is a third party insofar as the threat posed by Attacker 1 is con- cerned. This reformulated view, however, also has some concerning implications. First, consider a case in which I can either kill my Attacker or run away. Killing the Attacker would be impermissible and would wrong the Attacker, since it would be narrowly unnec- essary. But now imagine that my running away would very mildly harm a Bystander. I would still be morally required to run away, but now I would not wrong the Attacker by killing him. It seems odd to say that in both cases I am required not to kill the Attacker, but I only wrong him in one case. Second, now consider a case in which I could kill my Attacker, or mildly harm a Bystander, but that harming the Bystander would have enormous benefits (for example, it would save my life and five further lives). I would be required to harm the Bystander, but, on this view, would not wrong my Attacker if I chose to kill him, since killing him would be narrowly necessary. Now add an option to run away without harming anyone. According to the view under consideration, the addition of this impermissible option, an option I would be morally required to ignore, would make it the case that I now would wrong my Attacker if I chose to kill him, since killing him is now not narrowly necessary. A further general effect of separating necessity into narrow and wide necessity – with wide necessity operating external to liability – 10 I am grateful to an anonymous referee for comments here. DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE FOR AGGRESSORS 359 is that, as with having an external necessity principle more generally, this limits the significance of liability: Showing someone is liable, and that nobody else will be harmed, is not enough to justify harming them. There are further worries with the idea that narrow necessity is internal to liability and that liability is a one-to-one relation. Consider this case with one attacker and two victims: Case 3: Attacker attacks Victim 1 and Victim 2. Individually, each attack would license self- defence up to the narrowly proportionate limit of 10 units of harm. Only shooting the Attacker in the legs, imposing 15 units of harm, will prevent Attacker from completing his attacks. Bystander must decide whether to impose 15 units of harm.11 Now, this case may seem unproblematic. Intuitively, we clearly ought to handle the case as follows. First, the narrowly proportion- ate limit for the combined attacks is 20 units. Second, the necessary force is fifteen units. Therefore, the Attacker is liable to 15 units of force. But recall that we are investigating the conjunction of the claims that necessity is internal to liability, and that liability is a one-to-one relation. The above, intuitive response relies on combining the attacks to establish liability. However, if Claims 1 and 2 are correct, then liability for each attack must be established independently (because liability is one-to-one) and we must establish whether the harm necessary to stop each attack is narrowly proportionate given the aim of stopping that attack (since narrow necessity is internal to liability). So, we first ask whether 15 units is necessary and proportionate for preventing Attack 1. It is necessary, but not proportionate. And so Attacker is not liable to that harm in order to prevent Attack 1. The same is true of Attack 2. And so he is not liable to that harm either. Since he is not liable to 15 units in order to prevent Attack 1, nor 15 units to prevent Attack 2, he is not liable to 15 units in order to prevent both attacks. To be clear, this counter-intuitive outcome is not generated by assuming that liabilities cannot be aggregated. If, for example, Bys- tander could prevent the attack by inflicting 10 units that would prevent Attack 1, and, separately, 10 units that would prevent Attack 2, this would be permissible, since both these harms would be 11 I came to realise this problem with the one-to-one conception of necessity through engaging with Kimberly Kessler Ferzan’s exploration of liability and desert, ‘Defense and Desert: When Reasons Don’t Share,’ San Diego Law Review 55 (2018): 265–290. Ferzan’s work in turn engages with Uwe Steinhoff’s work. P. TOMLIN360 necessary and proportionate to preventing the particular attack, and so Attacker would be liable to both. (For example, if Bystander could shoot Attacker in both arms, independently causing him to drop the guns that threatens each Victim.) The trouble comes because of the conjunction of Claims 1 and 2. If necessity were external to liability (i.e., if Claim 1 were rejected), we could do things in this way: Attacker is liable to 10 units for Attack 1, and 10 units for Attack 2. Therefore, he is liable overall to 20 units of harm. A separate prin- ciple, external to questions of liability, namely necessity, confirms that the necessary harm of 15 units falls below the total amount of harm to which he is liable. However, if we reject Claim 2, and instead seek to establish Attacker’s joint liability for both attacks, then Attacker is potentially liable to up to 2o units of harm (combined narrow proportionality) and actually liable to 15 units (the harm necessary to prevent both attacks). Liability is established by joining the two attacks together. Consider, again, what combining Claims 1 and 2 together seems to require of us.12 Since we must establish liability on a one-to-one basis, and since we must keep necessity internal to liability, then liability must be established on a one-to-one basis. Thus, we are forced to say that 15 units of harm is too much to impose in order to stop Attack 1 and so is disproportionate. And the same is true of imposing 15 units in order to stop Attack 2. However, two separate harms – of 10 units each – would be allowed if they independently stopped each attack. So, if Claims 1 and 2 are true, then we would be allowed to impose 20 units of harm on Attacker, but not 15. This is an odd result, for surely necessity should require us to inflict 15 units of harm over 20 units of harm in order to achieve the same end. Our consideration of the above cases reveals the following. First, necessity (or something like it) must surely consider various harmful options that spread across attacks. Second, it follows from this that one of the following is true: (1) liability is not a one-to-one relation, (2) that necessity is external to liability, or (3) necessity is not the only principle that helps us to adjudicate between proportionate defensive options. Third, if (2) or (3) is the case, then there are external limits on one-to-one liability which seek to limit harm across attacks. If this is true, the claim that liability is a one-to-one relation is 12 I am grateful to Helen Frowe for useful discussion here. DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE FOR AGGRESSORS 361 less powerful than we initially might be tempted to think. For lia- bility is not, then, enough to grant us permission to harm, even if nobody who is not liable is in the frame. Although I have speculated here that what we call ‘necessity’ may actually be an amalgamation of concerns or principles, I will largely leave that speculation behind from this point on. Whatever we call it, we are morally required to minimize harms among liable attackers, and this goes beyond the instruction to avoid gratuitous harm. I want to investigate this requirement further, and will call it ‘necessity’ for ease. V. SEPARATE ATTACKS It is tempting to see narrow proportionality and necessity as two limits on defensive harm, with the main difference between them being that narrow proportionality is concerned with features of the threat (‘what you did was out of proportion given the threat I posed!’) while necessity is concerned with the comparative merits of the options available to the defensive agent (‘you didn’t need to do that, you could have done this!’). We now see, however, that, regardless of whether they are internal or external to liability, narrow proportionality and necessity appear to work quite differently in other ways. Narrow propor- tionality looks at the one-to-one relation between attacker and vic- tim (though it can be aggregated, as in Case 3), while necessity seeks to minimize harm across narrowly proportionate defensive options, sometimes directing us to harm one attacker rather than another (as in Case 1), or a bystander over an attacker (as in Case 2). Thus far we have considered cases in which the attacks were in some senses separate, giving rise to different one-to-one relations, but the defensive options were linked by producing the same effects. However, if we extend the analysis thus far, we get some potentially controversial results. Consider Cases 4 and 5. Case 4: Attacker 1 attacks Victim, threatening 100 units of harm. The attack can be prevented by inflicting 100 units of harm on Attacker 1. Attacker 2 also attacks Victim, also threatening 100 units of harm. The attack can be prevented by inflicting 50 units of harm on Attacker 2. Victim can only prevent one of the attacks. Case 5: Attacker 1 attacks Victim 1, threatening 100 units of harm. The attack can be prevented by inflicting 100 units of harm on Attacker 1. Attacker 2 attacks Victim 2, also threatening 100 units of harm. The attack can be prevented by inflicting 50 units of harm on Attacker 2. Neither victim can prevent the attack against herself or the other, but Bystander can prevent one. P. TOMLIN362 The analysis thus far suggests that the requirement to minimize harm stretches across attacks, and attackers. Thus, it would seem to instruct Victim in Case 4 to inflict 50 units of harm on Attacker 2. She is going to suffer 100 units of harm either way, and so the requirement to minimize harm states that she must inflict 50 units of harm rather than 100 units of harm in order to avoid an additional 100 units of harm to herself. Some may find this counter-intuitive. They may think both responses are both narrowly proportionate and necessary, and that Victim can choose as she wishes whom to harm. Both attackers have made themselves liable and may be harmed. But the problem with such a view is that it seems to rely on an account of necessity that was rejected in the previous cases. Cases 1–3 show that necessity, or something like it, gives us guidance that we ought to minimize harm across attackers. This expansive understanding of necessity seems even more controversial when the attacks are fully separate, as in Case 5. In this case, our analysis thus far suggests that Bystander ought to save Victim 2, since doing so minimizes harm and all else is equal. If we transport this expansive view of necessity to war, we will generate some very controversial conclusions. On this view of necessity, if we have two wars we might enter in defence of others, both of which will do the same amount of good, we would be required to enter the war which would do the least harm to culpable aggressors, even though both wars, considered independently, are necessary and proportionate. This is controversial. Especially since there is no principled reason to restrict our options to war. Scholars have noted a controversy about proportionality and what counter- factual is involved: When states decide to go to war, they need to compare ‘going to war’ with ‘not going to war’. How, several philosophers have asked, should we fill out ‘not going to war’? It could be a very demanding standard: A war might be proportionate only if the good it achieves compared with the very best options available to the state is worth the death and destruction involved.13 But 13 David Mellow, ‘Counterfactuals and the Proportionality Criterion,’ Ethics and International Affairs 20 (2006): 439–454; Thomas Hurka, ‘Proportionality and Necessity’ in Larry May and Emily Crookston eds., War: Essays in Political Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008); Kieran Ober- man, ‘War and Poverty,’ Philosophical Studies (forthcoming: https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/ s11098-017-1012-4). DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE FOR AGGRESSORS 363 philosophers have been slower to notice that there is also a similar issue related to necessity.14 Necessity requires us to compare options, but how should we construct our option set? On the expansive view currently under discussion, a war might be necessary only if there is no other way to achieve a comparable level of good or prevention of harm without causing as much harm. Therefore, necessity demands that we should, for example, alleviate poverty over going to war. This may seem overly demanding. We can avoid these demanding entailments if we allow that necessity can apply across persons, but demand that it be restricted to a particular ‘situation’. If we can cordon necessity off in some way, we can say that necessity only applies to the choice between some options, and not to, for example, the choice between a war and alleviating poverty. We might then appeal to some independent ‘minimizing harm’ principle that advises us (or requires us) to minimize harm, but is not related to liability. This proposal is attractive. Indeed, some seem to think it is obviously the way to handle the cases discussed in this paper. I am attracted to this view, but, as I am going to explain, I think it is hard to get it to work. VI. LIMITING NECESSITY’S REACH? Necessity rules on which of our available options we should take. If we are to cordon off necessity, preventing it from applying to a choice between war and alleviating poverty but allowing it to apply to choices about whether to harm an attacker more or less, we must have a principled way of determining the scope of the options to which the necessity principle applies. I think a necessity principle with a limited scope intuitively offers us the best picture, but finding the right way to restrict necessity’s reach is difficult. That is what I want to show in this section. The idea of this section is to lay down a challenge to anyone who denies that necessity dictates that we ought to alleviate poverty rather than go to war: How do we restrict necessity’s reach? The most obvious way to try to delineate a ‘situation’ or set of options to which necessity applies is to do with the people involved. The clearest examples of the necessity principle being breached in- 14 A notable exception here is Kieran Oberman, ‘War and Poverty’; and ‘Killing and Rescuing,’ Philosophical Review 129 (2020). In these papers Oberman argues for a very expansive view of necessity. P. TOMLIN364 volve harming someone more than we need to. If individuals are wronged by being harmed unnecessarily, we might try to limit necessity’s reach by restricting its application to options that harm the same people. For example, we might try this principle: Limiting Principle 1: Necessity applies only to options which harm the same persons. This principle is obviously flawed. First, necessity would not apply in this case: Case 6: Attackers 1 and 2 attack Victim. They can be stopped by killing Attacker 1, or by killing both Attackers. According to Limiting Principle 1, killing both Attackers would not be condemned by the necessity principle, since the two options available harm different sets of people, and so the necessity principle would not apply across these two options. Here’s another principle: Limiting Principle 2: Necessity applies only to options in which some of the same persons will be harmed. This principle has four problems. First, necessity would not apply to the decision in Case 1. Second, this principle would render the jus in bello necessity condition next-to-toothless. Consider this case: Case 7: Platoon needs to capture an enemy base. If they attack from the south, they will need to kill one sentry, Sentry 1. If they attack from the north, they will need to kill Sentries 2-21. This is a clear case of where we would expect the jus in bello necessity principle to apply. According to Limiting Principle 2, it does not. So long as killing 20 enemy soldiers is proportionate, then Platoon should feel free to attack from the north or the south. We might try to set aside Case 7 by claiming that since the enemy soldiers all fight for the same army, this is a special case, and that necessity can apply to groups of people. But, first, this would fly in the face of much contemporary just war theory. And, second, we would no longer be able to compare harms to our own soldiers and civilians with harms to enemy soldiers and civilians. Third, the necessity condition would not apply to this case: Case 8: Country A is threated by Countries B and C. Defending A from either B or C will cause the other to back off. Country D can defeat B with a loss of 100 of B’s soldiers, or C with a loss of 10,000 of C’s soldiers. The third problem with Limiting Principle 2 is that necessity should clearly condemn killing when the same objective can be achieved DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE FOR AGGRESSORS 365 without killing anyone. Limiting Principle 2 only seems to apply to choices between options in which someone is going to be harmed. And if we extend it to options in which nobody will be harmed, the principle will then apply to the choice between killing in war and not killing and alleviating poverty. The fourth problem with Limiting Principle 2 is that it is open to what I will call ‘overlapping problems’. Since I discuss these in more depth below (concerning overlapping populations of who is to be saved), I will not detail these issues here. An alternative to focusing on the parties to be harmed is to limit necessity’s reach by focusing on the people to be saved. As Kieran Oberman observes, when we ask whether harm is necessary, it can only be necessary or unnecessary to achieving some goal.15 Since, in cases of both self-defence and other-defence, our goal is to save people, we might try limiting necessity by looking at options which save the same people. For example, in Case 1, Victim aims to save herself. How much harm, she might ask, is necessary to achieve this aim? Therefore, we might use this principle: Limiting Principle 3: Necessity applies only to options in which the same people are to be saved. This principle implies that if we could kill Ted to save 100 people, or kill nobody and save the same 100 plus Bill, necessity would not dictate that we choose the latter option, since the same people are not saved in both options. We could amend Limiting Principle 3 to avoid this implication if we allowed necessity to apply only to options in which at least the same people are saved (i.e., to options which save some core group and options Pareto superior to those). However, even under this revised reading, in a war context, necessity would have no bearing on this choice:16 Case 9: Country A aims to save Country B from Country C. This involves sending troops into Country B. A is confident it will win the war, but there will be civilian casualties. If A’s army enters B from the east, 1000 civilians from the eastern district will be killed. If A enters B from the west, 10,000 civilians from the western district will be killed. Here, since different people will be killed, different people will be saved. If A chooses to enter from the east, the 10,000 westerners who would be killed under the alternative plan will instead be saved. We could instead try this principle: 15 Oberman, ‘War and Poverty’; ‘Killing and Rescuing’. 16 For related discussion, see Oberman, ‘War and Poverty’, section 5. P. TOMLIN366 Limiting Principle 4: Necessity applies only to options in which some of the same people are saved. Here is my worry with this principle. Consider the following ‘overlap case’: Case 10: Aggressor attacks Victims 1, 2, 3 and 4. Option 1 saves Victims 1 and 2, at a cost of 10 units of harm to Aggressor. Option 2 saves Victims 2 and 3 at a cost of 100 units. Option 3 saves Victims 3 and 4 at a cost of 1000 units. Now, compared pairwise under Limiting Principle 4, necessity says we must choose Option 1 over Option 2, Option 2 over Option 3, but that we have a free choice between Options 1 and 3, since necessity doesn’t apply to that choice. So, necessity doesn’t necessarily tell us to do anything regarding the choice between Options 1, 2 and 3. Perhaps this is not a problem: Perhaps necessity is not an issue of pairwise comparisons, but of comparing a full range of options. Provided that Option 1 saves some of the same people as Option 2, and Option 2 saves some of the same people as Option 3, perhaps necessity applies to the choice between all three options. However, if we view necessity in that way, then two new worries arise. The first is that necessity faces a difficulty from the ‘principle of irrelevant alternatives’. According to Limiting Principle 4, provided there is a ‘chain’ of options in which at least some of the same people are saved in adjacent options, then necessity applies across the whole range of options. So, in Case 10, you should select Option 1, since 1>2>3. Let’s now remove Option 2. Removing Option 2 which you weren’t going to choose anyway, means that you now have a free choice between Options 1 and 3. More importantly, Limiting Principle 4 does not necessarily mean that necessity would not apply to a choice between war and allevi- ating poverty. Often a choice between a war and alleviating poverty will involve saving at least one person in common. But even if not, we simply need to be able to construct a ‘chain’ of options (however morally implausible some of them may be) and the options of war and alleviating poverty will then become subject to the necessity constraint. For example, imagine that we are deciding whether to militarily intervene in Country A or alleviate poverty in Country B. Provided we also have the (morally implausible) option of devoting all of our resources to saving only Lukas from Country A and only DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE FOR AGGRESSORS 367 Max from Country B, then necessity applies, according to Limiting Principle 4, to the choice between war and alleviating poverty. I don’t have any answers here. My intuitions tell me that, at least when it comes to harming the potentially liable, necessity is re- stricted to particular defensive situations. However, it is very hard to find a principled way of restricting necessity. VII. NECESSITY AND NARROW PROPORTIONALITY Necessity and narrow proportionality are usually thought of as independent tests. Narrow proportionality establishes upper limits on harm, necessity tells us to minimize harm. Our job as defensive agents is to check that they coincide: that the option which mini- mizes harm is below the threshold set by (aggregated) narrow pro- portionality. In this section, I want to argue that the relationship between narrow proportionality and necessity is potentially more complicated than this. I will argue that whether a harmful action can be deemed nec- essary involves looking at something I call ‘narrow proportionality shortfall’. If I am right, this shows two things. First, even if necessity is external to liability, the relationships between the various concepts remain complex. We cannot simply say that narrow proportionality sets an internal limit based on pairwise comparisons, whilst necessity sets a fully independent external limit that is concerned with aggregate harm, since narrow proportionality is an important con- cept in deciding the permissible distribution of harms across a plu- rality of responsible threats. Second, since necessity is sensitive to narrow proportionality, this shows that they are two distinct criteria. This is in contrast to some recent scholarship that has sought to show that necessity and proportionality are but two sides of the same coin.17 Consider this case: Case 11: Victim is attacked by two unconnected persons simultaneously. It is narrowly pro- portionate to impose 200 units of harm on Attacker 1, and 20 units of harm on Attacker 2. Repelling either attack will cause the other attacker to abandon their attack. Attacker 1 can be repelled with 21 units of harm. Attacker 2 can be repelled with 20 units of harm. In this case, it is more harmful to repel Attacker 1 than Attacker 2. 17 Lazar, ‘Necessity in Self-Defense and War,’ pp. 17–18; Thomas Hurka, ‘Proportionality in the Morality of War,’ Philosophy & Public Affairs 33 (2005): 34–66, at pp. 37–38. P. TOMLIN368 So, any view under which necessity merely requires us to minimize harm, or to minimize priority-weighted harm, would instruct Victim to harm Attacker 2. But, in my view, necessity instructs Victim to harm Attacker 1. Seth Lazar and Jeff McMahan argue that necessity does not demand that we minimize harm (all else equal) but rather that we minimize morally-weighted harm (all else equal). That is because when we must choose, for example, between a harm to an attacker and a slightly lesser harm to an innocent bystander, we should harm the attacker who has created the situation in which someone must be harmed.18 My claim here is that harms to culpable aggressors can also have different moral weightings. Narrow proportionality represents the maximum possible harm that can be justified under a liability justification for achieving some specific good. In Case 11, harming Attacker 1 involves inflicting roughly one-tenth of the harm to which he is potentially liable. Repelling Attacker 2 involves inflicting all of the harm to which he is potentially liable. Necessity should take account of this. Just as necessity should distinguish between harms done to the innocent and those done to the liable, so it should distinguish within harms done to the liable. It can do this if the moral weighting of harm takes account of what I call the ‘narrow proportionality shortfall’ – that is, how far short of the maximum potential liability, or narrowly pro- portionate limit, a harmful action is. In Case 11, the narrow pro- portionality shortfall of harming Attacker 1 with 21 units is 179. The narrow proportionality shortfall of harming Attacker 2 with 20 units is zero. This huge discrepancy in narrow proportionality shortfall explains why we should harm Attacker 1, even though this does more harm. Case 11 shows that necessity is concerned with narrow propor- tionality shortfall. There are several ways that we might incorporate this concern with narrow proportionality shortfall into a theory of necessity. Here are three. First is the extreme view, in which this concern for narrow proportionality shortfall is the only concern when considering harms to potentially liable parties. In other words, there is no concern with absolute levels of harm, and a concern only with narrow proportionality shortfall. According to this view, nar- row proportionality sets a baseline against which to measure harm. 18 Lazar, ‘Necessity in Self-Defense and War,’ p. 6; McMahan, ‘The Limits of Self-Defense’. DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE FOR AGGRESSORS 369 Here is how this view would handle Case 11. Since Attacker 1 is potentially liable to 200 units of harm, the ‘baseline’ against which we measure harms to him becomes -200 units. Essentially, that means that we will prefer 200 units of harm to him over a single unit of harm to an innocent person (whose baseline remains at 0). Only once we have filled the full quota of harms to which you are potentially liable will we look at harming an innocent person. Since Attacker 2 is potentially liable to 20 units of harm, his baseline becomes -20 units. Therefore, any distribution of harm in which Attacker 1 has fewer than 180 units of harm is to be preferred to any distribution in which Attacker 2 is harmed at all, because only once Attacker 1 has received 180 units of harm will the two be on equal footing. I think this view has a compelling logic, though it is counter-intuitive. Should we prefer 180 units of harm to Attacker 1 over one unit of harm to Attacker 2? Second is the proportion view. In Case 11, 21 units of harm is roughly 10 percent of what Attacker 1 is potentially liable to, while 20 units of harm is 100 percent of what Attacker 2 is potentially liable to. We might think necessity dictates that we should prefer which- ever harm is a lesser proportion of the harm to which the Attacker is potentially liable. However, this again could generate cases in which we should prefer hundreds of units of harm to one potentially liable attacker over a single unit of harm to another. Third is the mixed view. On this view, the concerns outlined in either or both of the extreme view and the proportion view are coupled with a concern to minimize absolute levels of harm. I prefer this view. But the central point is that, whichever of these we choose, if we accept that narrow proportionality shortfall matters to necessity, then the following three things follow. First, this is further evidence that, if necessity is internal to liability, then liability is not a one-to-one relation – necessity (and thus liability) chooses which of the potentially liable persons we should harm, based on facts about other persons. Second, it shows that necessity and narrow propor- tionality are independent concepts, one of which informs the other. Third, it shows that a moral consideration (namely, necessity) prefers harms that are further away from narrow proportionality thresholds to those that are close to the maximum liability. If, all else equal, necessity demands that we maximize narrow proportionality short- P. TOMLIN370 fall, then it shows morality to be sensitive to how close harms get to the narrow proportionality threshold. This final point will become important when we consider sequential aggressor cases. VIII. NECESSITY AND DISTRIBUTION Thus far we have largely considered cases in which we must choose which of multiple simultaneous aggressors we ought to harm. However, sometimes we might also have choices of harming more than one aggressor, and different distributions of harm may be available. For example, consider this case: Case 12: Victim is attacked by Attacker 1 and Attacker 2. It will be narrowly proportionate to inflict 100 units of harm on either. Victim has three defensive options: 100 units of harm to Attacker 1; 100 units of harm to Attacker 2; and 51 units of harm to both. In my view, Victim ought to harm both with 51 units, even though this is more harm overall. This cannot be because we must minimize harm. It also cannot be because of maximizing narrow proportion- ality shortfall – the total narrow proportionality shortfall of harming one of the attackers is 100, the total narrow proportionality shortfall of harming both is 98. Most straightforwardly, this case shows that we should be con- cerned not only with harm, but with the distribution of harm. Before we delve into what this distributive concern is, if we accept that in Case 12 Victim ought to inflict 51 units of harm on both attackers, then we face a conceptual choice. One is to fold this distributive concern (whatever it may be) into necessity – allowing distributive concerns to affect the moral weighting of harm. Another is to introduce such concerns as an independent desideratum.19 The cost of this position, however, is that necessity is relegated from hard side-constraint to defeasible desideratum, since this independent distributive concern would allow us to depart from necessity’s rec- ommendations. Therefore, I think it makes more sense to fold this concern into necessity. So, some kind of distributive concern should be added to the moral weighting of harm. But this doesn’t show that we must be concerned with (say) an equal distribution of harm. This distributive concern might itself be sensitive to narrow proportionality shortfall. Consider the following case: 19 Lars Christie suggested this to me. DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE FOR AGGRESSORS 371 Case 13: Victim is attacked by two unconnected persons simultaneously. It would be narrowly proportionate to harm Attacker 1 with 40 units of harm, and Attacker 2 with 20 units of harm. The following defensive options are available. Option A: Both attackers are harmed with 20 units of harm. Option B: Attacker 1 receives 30 units of harm, and Attacker 2 receives 10 units of harm. In this case, the total amount of harm (40 units) and the total narrow proportionality shortfall (20 units) remain constant between the two options. All that changes is the distribution of harm (in Option A 20- 20, in Option B 30-10), and the distribution of the narrow proportionality shortfall (in Option A 20-0, in Option B 10-10). My own view is that necessity requires Option B in this case. Were necessity focused on minimizing narrowly proportionate harm, we’d expect it to be indifferent between Options A and B. If necessity cared about minimizing harm and distributing that harm as equally as possible, we’d expect it to prefer Option A. Here are two views which would account for preferring Option B. Equality of Narrow Proportionality Shortfall: All else equal, fairness between attackers requires equalizing the distance from the narrowly proportionate limit of harm to which they are potentially liable. Shifted-Baseline Prioritarianism: Units of harm are not equally bad – they get worse the more harm there is. When someone is potentially liable to some harm, this shifts the ‘baseline’ against which we measure how bad the harm is. For example, the 201st unit of harm to somebody who is potentially liable to 200 units of harm should be considered of equal badness to the 21st unit of harm to someone who is liable to 20 units of harm, and to the first unit of harm to someone who is not liable to any harm. The first unit of harm to someone who is potentially liable to 20 units of harm equally weighted to the 181st unit to someone who is potentially liable to 200 units. The idea with Shifted-Baseline Prioritarianism is that harm gets progressively worse, as in standard prioritarianism,20 but narrowly proportionate harms are discounted.21 Importantly, though, not all units of narrowly proportionate harm are given the same discount: Those closest to the narrowly proportionate limit are given very little discount. Those further away are given progressively more and more discount. This position would give us the advantage of caring both about total harm, and about total narrow proportionality shortfall (the view that I found most attractive in the previous section) with one underlying explanation – we care about total morally weighted and priority-weighted harm, and the priority-weight- 20 Derek Parfit, Equality or Priority? (Kansas: University of Kansas, 1991). 21 This may, therefore, be a specification of Richard Arneson’s ‘Responsibility-Catering Prioritari- anism.’ Richard J. Arneson, ‘Luck Egalitarianism and Prioritarianism,’ Ethics 110 (2000): 339–349. P. TOMLIN372 ing baseline is shifted by narrow proportionality. I will not investigate further which of these two options we should endorse. It may be that which is preferable turns on deeper questions concerning distributive ethics that I cannot venture into here, although it may be that narrowly proportionate harms are sui generis, and we can, say, endorse prioritarianism within the limits of narrow proportionality while rejecting it outside. Similarly, we may endorse equality under normal circumstances, but find the idea of having to make sure we treat attackers fairly unpersuasive. Instead, I want to draw out several implications of the views suggested. It seems that both counsel that harms closer to the nar- row proportionality limit are, in some sense, something to be additionally wary of, or harder to justify. They are not the same as harms further from the narrow proportionality limit. In Equality of Narrow Proportionality Shortfall, this commitment manifests itself in a concern to fairly distribute the avoidance of these harms, rather than the harms themselves. In Shifted-Baseline Prioritarianism, this mani- fests itself in weighting harms closer to the limit more heavily than those further away. One implication of this concerns some cases that are, conceptu- ally and normatively, difficult. The most clear cases for the principle of necessity – both in terms of whether it applies as a principle, and in terms of what it recommends – are those in which the exact same good can be achieved by more or less harm to the same person (i.e., what we have called gratuitous harm cases). But there are also cases in which our options vary both in terms of how much harm and how much good we will do. For example, consider this case: Case 14: Attacker threatens Victim with 40 units of harm. Victim can prevent 39 units of harm by imposing 60 units of harm on Attacker, or she can prevent all 40 units by imposing 70 units of harm on Attacker. The narrow proportionality limit is 100 units. In some ways, choosing between these options is clearly an issue for the principle of necessity. Both options are narrowly proportionate, so we have a choice between narrowly proportionate options, and it is necessity’s job to select between such options. But in another way, it is more like a proportionality calculation. That is because, in essence, Victim’s decision is whether ten units of additional harm to DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE FOR AGGRESSORS 373 Attacker can be justified to prevent one unit of additional harm to herself.22 My point here is simply this. If we allow that narrowly propor- tionate harms are harder to justify the closer to the narrowly pro- portionate limit they get, this will impact on how we treat such cases: This isn’t a case of weighing one unit of harm to an innocent person against ten units of harm to an aggressor, which is how such cases are usually discussed. It is a case of weighing one unit of harm to an innocent (which may itself be priority-weighted) against ten units which range from 40 to 30 in terms of narrow proportionality shortfall. Keeping the unit of harm to the Victim constant, such a unit may justify ten units of harm to an additional aggressor who hasn’t yet been harmed, but may not justify ten units of additional harm to an aggressor who is already going to receive 60 units from a limit of 100. IX. SEQUENTIAL ATTACKS Thus far, I have focussed on simultaneous threat cases: cases in which a plurality of aggressors poses threats at the same time. In closing, I’d like to apply some of the lessons that we have drawn from simultaneous-threat cases to sequential-threat cases. There is an important puzzle concerning sequential-threat cases. According to Frances Kamm, there is no limit to the number of aggressors whom I could kill in order to save my own life. Since killing in order to fend off each attack, taken on its own, is necessary and narrowly proportionate, Kamm reasons that there can be no objection to the collection of defensive actions: ‘One compares the wrong to be avoided with what would have to be done to each wrongdoer one at a time, and if there is no violation of propor- tionality in any individual comparison then there is no violation tout court.’23 Yet many of us are deeply troubled by the idea that, provided we can kill one aggressor in order to achieve some goal, we can kill an infinite number of aggressors in order to achieve that goal. Is there some way to avoid this implication? There is, of course. Since the implication arises from the picture of self-defence and war that has 22 Lazar, ‘Necessity in Self-Defense and War’; McMahan, ‘The Limits of Self-Defense’. 23 F.M. Kamm, Ethics for Enemies (New York: Oxford University Press, 2011), pp. 133–134. P. TOMLIN374 emerged from both ancient and recent scholarship on this issue, we could rip up this picture and start again, making sure that the new picture doesn’t have the unpalatable implication that we can kill infinite aggressors. This is too hasty – this model serves us well in general, and so we should do all we can to preserve its core con- ceptual and normative commitments. Ripping it up would be to throw the baby out with the bathwater. Alternatively, we could stipulate that one cannot kill an infinite number of aggressors. But this response is ad hoc.24 To forewarn: I do not claim to solve this puzzle in what follows. But I do think that what we have learned about liability and necessity in simultaneous-attack cases might help us with this puzzle. First, it is important to understand that necessity applies across attacks and is a moral concern for minimizing harm not just within a one-to-one relationship but across such relationships. Several philosophers have suggested that there may be some countervailing reasons against harming those whom it would be individually nar- rowly proportionate to harm, but which derive from aggregation of narrowly proportionate harms. For example, David Rodin argues that wide proportionality is concerned with the way that harms to the liable add up, while Jeff McMahan proposes an additional form of proportionality – proportionality in the aggregate.25 McMahan’s proposal in particular may seem somewhat mysterious. In defence of the existence of proportionality in the aggregate, McMahan is unable to point toward much other than that it gets the intuitively right answers – in other words, it sails a little too close to the ad hoc response to the puzzle. What we have discovered in the present paper is perhaps partial evidence for the existence of something like proportionality in the aggregate – there are other elements of defensive morality that work in similar ways. They constrain harms and dictate choices of harms between multiple aggressors, even when each harm, were it the only option, would be proportionate, necessary, and permissible. Neces- sity reveals a concern for the comparative lessening of such harms. But wouldn’t it be odd if morality were keen to limit such harm 24 I am grateful to Victor Tadros for discussion which helped me to see these twin dangers. 25 McMahan, ‘Liability, Proportionality, and the Number of Aggressors’; Rodin, ‘Justifying Harm’. DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE FOR AGGRESSORS 375 comparatively but not absolutely? If so, proportionality in the aggregate would seem to be on a somewhat firmer basis. Relatedly, McMahan in particular takes the apparent one-to-one nature of liability to be what generates the puzzle. But we now see that either liability is not one-to-one (if necessity is internal to lia- bility), or that liability is subject to external checks (if necessity is external to liability). Therefore, there are other parts of defensive morality that already operate in ways that are similar to propor- tionality in the aggregate. This makes McMahan’s response to Kamm’s puzzle less mysterious. Second, in addition to these general points about necessity, we have found a more direct link between necessity and narrow pro- portionality. Necessity takes account of narrow proportionality. It is concerned with maximizing narrow proportionality shortfall, and with its distribution. Here, I think there is potentially the beginnings of a justification and understanding of the way in which narrowly proportionate actions can add up to a disproportionate course of action. Necessity seems to prefer harms further away from the narrow proportionality threshold than those nearer to it. This sug- gests that harms close to the narrow proportionality threshold can be justified, but are worse, harder to justify, or to be avoided more, than those further away. My tentative view is that these observations can provide a firmer backing for the kinds of restrictions on harming responsible threats articulated by McMahan and Rodin. McMahan’s proportionality in the aggregate could, I think, be understood as the way in which narrow proportionality shortfall can aggregate. We have seen that necessity prefers harms that are a greater distance below the narrow proportionality line, even if those just under the line could be jus- tified in a single attacker case. If a series of harms are close to the line, then the same concerns that motivate necessity’s preference for harms further away from the line could motivate a concern with the aggregation of harms close to the line. The thought here is simple: Necessity is concerned with minimizing ‘only just’ proportionate harms. If there are differentiations within narrowly proportionate harms, such that we are concerned with how close to the line harms get, we might also be concerned with how these harms aggregate. P. TOMLIN376 In particular, the Shifted-Baseline Priority View would seem to lessen the gap between narrow and wide proportionality. It doesn’t eliminate the difference, but it does mean that the two kinds of proportionality are not as different as may first appear. What narrow proportionality does, on this view, is (differentially) discount harms to the potentially liable. These harms still count though – they’re not morally free shots – and so many harms that are right on the narrow proportionality threshold can aggregate just as harms to the innocent can aggregate. This view of narrow proportionality as a progressive discounting mechanism might therefore provide some backing for Rodin’s view. This also would explain why proportionality in the aggregate can differentiate between culpable and responsible threats. Responsible and culpable threats are both liable to be killed in order to save a life. However, we should differentiate between de facto limits to liability and de jure limits to liability. De facto, the limit will often be the same – killing is just about the worst thing you can do to a person, and both are liable to be killed. But culpable aggressors can be liable to far greater harms than those they threaten to impose on others – for example, it is proportionate to kill a culpable aggressor to avoid being paralyzed, even if one will have many good years as a para- lyzed person. Therefore, the de jure limit to avoid being killed by a culpable aggressor is far higher than death, and far higher than the de jure limit on a responsible threat. Therefore, when we kill many responsible threats, we impart many harms very close to the narrow proportionality threshold. This is not the case when we kill many culpable aggressors (if the good at stake is a person’s life). It may be that there is some limit to the number of culpable aggressors we can kill to save a single life (I think there is) but it will be far higher than the number of responsible threats. I won’t pretend that what I have said in this section is any more than a sketch of a defence of McMahan’s and Rodin’s responses to Kamm’s view. But thinking through simultaneous-aggressor cases, and what we learn about liability, necessity, and narrow propor- tionality from such cases, certainly makes Kamm’s logic seem less compelling. In particular, I would now reject the thought that lia- bility is simply a one-to-one relation, and Kamm’s view seem com- pelling in part because of that assumption. DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE FOR AGGRESSORS 377 X. CONCLUDING THOUGHTS This paper has covered a lot of ground. The common thread throughout has been thinking about cases involving more than one attacker, and how we should distribute harms between those attackers. Consideration of these cases raise major issues in terms of how to understand the principle of necessity, its relationship to lia- bility and narrow proportionality, and its scope. In particular, I have argued for the following: 1. Necessity ought to tell us which of two potentially liable parties to harm. It follows from this that (a) necessity is either not internal to liability, or liability is not a one-to-one relation; and (b) if necessity is external to liability, then necessity, as an external principle, takes ac- count of the distribution of harms across attackers. 2. Necessity possibly has different components or concerns, or is possibly an amalgam of distinct principles (for example, avoiding gratuitous harm, minimizing morally-weighted harm, distributing morally- weighted harm). Some of these concerns or principles may be internal to liability (narrow necessity), some external (wide necessity). 3. Once we realise that necessity applies across individuals, it becomes very difficult to cordon off necessity so that it applies to the choice between some options and not others. We must either supply a principled way of restricting necessity’s scope, or accept that it has a far greater reach than traditionally supposed, not only directing us in how and whether we go to war to pursue some end, but whether we pursue that end or another. 4. Necessity should be sensitive to ‘narrow proportionality shortfall’ – that is, how closely the various harms one is deciding between are to the narrow proportionality threshold. 5. Necessity should take account of distributive concerns, including the distribution of narrow proportionality shortfall. I articulated two principles for doing so, Equality of Narrow Proportionality Shortfall and Shifted-Baseline Prioritarianism. 6. These findings may help us in thinking about sequential attacks. That (a) liability is not a one-to-one relation, or morality allows external checks on liable harms that seek to limit them, and (b) necessity cares about the distribution of harm and narrow proportionality shortfall, may provide some support for the idea of ‘proportionality in the P. TOMLIN378 aggregate’ in sequential-attacker cases, a notion which suggests that you cannot kill an infinite number of liable aggressors if your cause would allow you to kill one. OPEN ACCESS This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 Inter- national License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article’s Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article’s Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http:// creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/. Department of Philosophy University of Warwick, Coventry, UK E-mail: patrick.tomlin@warwick.ac.uk Publisher’s Note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE FOR AGGRESSORS 379 http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ Distributive Justice for Aggressors Abstract Introduction Liability, Narrow Proportionality, and Necessity: the basic model Two Claims about Liability Necessity and Liability Separate Attacks Limiting Necessity’s Reach? Necessity and Narrow Proportionality Necessity and Distribution Sequential Attacks Concluding Thoughts Open Access work_bkfcda5vbjevjfijgk5dd35eju ---- BJGP Back pages-Master[1] Contents British Journal of General Practice, November 2009 871 Viewpoint BackPagesTHE 872 ESSAY Diagnostic safety-netting Susanna Almond, David Mant and Matthew Thompson 874 COMMENTARY Roger Neighbour 875 ESSAY Little Miss Why’s learning journey Tara George 876 Diagnostic delusions Mike Fitzpatrick 877 VIEWPOINT Role models, radicals, and reactionaries Keith Taylor 878 VIEWPOINT General practice at the margins: a student’s experience of homelessness Kirsty Duncan 879 VIEWPOINT A conferring Dermot Halpin 880 DIGEST Book review Iain Bamforth 882 Monsters Saul Miller GENES, GENDER, SPORT, AND JUSTICE In August the papers were full of Caster Semenya, the South African athlete who won the 800 metres at the world championships in Berlin, but who, because of her outstanding performance was to be tested to establish whether she was eligible to compete as a woman. In statements this was described as ‘a medical matter’.1 Presumably the suspicion is that Semenya has androgen insensitivity, or another metabolic anomaly which leads someone with XY chromosomes to have a female body. No doubt when the results are available it will again be headline news. The case raises questions about gender, but also about fairness in sport and the role of medicine in this. Firstly there is the wellbeing of the individual athlete. Whatever the situation, it must be very unpleasant to have a fundamental aspect of your identify dissected in public. Surely the system could better protect athletes’ feelings and medical confidentiality. If sexual chromosomes are crucial to eligibility in sports then perhaps participants should be required to produce evidence privately before competitions, rather than questions being raised in public post hoc. The division of humanity into male and female is fundamental in most societies. At birth we are defined by our gender and weight; other distinguishing characteristics come later. But few things are entirely black and white, and some people have ambiguous genitalia, or chromosomes and a body form which does not fit in the usual way; conditions often grouped together as ‘intersex’. As well as difficulties inseparable from some of these conditions, like infertility, these people often feel stigmatised and marginalised.2 Men and women compete separately in many sports. We take this for granted; yet in other areas of life — work, financial affairs, academic achievement — such separation would be seen as sexual discrimination or debated as affirmative action. Why do we treat sport differently? There are of course significant differences in physiological averages which mean that in some sports women would be marginalised if they had to compete against men. But if on the whole, justice and human flourishing are better served by this arrangement, how do we draw the line between the genders? What is more basic; our body form, our psychological self-image, or our chromosomes? And how can we avoid excluding those who straddle these divisions from sport? More fundamentally, what does fairness demand in relation to genetic inheritance in sport? Should we judge athletes on the basis of effort or performance? It’s not just genes carried on the XY chromosomes that affect performance; people with particular body types as a result of their genetic inheritance perform very differently in many sports. This, like androgen sensitivity, is not under their control. Why should we accept these differences but not chromosomal anomalies? We tend to treat conditions differently according to how complex their causes are and how well we understand them. If stronger muscles result from an anomaly we can describe and name, we might consider this unfair and exclude the athlete; if it comes from a fortuitous combination of many genes, not all well understood, we may not. Some would argue that distinctions between the treatment of dyslexia and poor literacy, between ADHD and bad behaviour, between psychopathy and evil, are similarly based on differences between what we now understand and what we do not yet understand, rather than on morally valid distinctions. If this is so then we need to be cautious, because medicine can be abused to support unjust practices and make unfair distinctions. Also we may find our moral judgements shifting as our understanding increases, because they are built on shifting sands — an ethical version of the ‘God of the Gaps’ problem. How to resolve these issues is not clear: I certainly don’t have the answers. But we do need to ask questions which go a lot deeper than what sort of chromosomes Caster Semenya has. Leaked reports, suggesting that Semenya has androgen insensitivity, or another metabolic anomaly which leads someone with XY chromosomes to have a female body form, led to further media debate. Peter D Toon REFERENCES 1. Hart S. Caster Semenya’s gender test results force IAAF to call in outside help. Telegraph 2009; 8 Sep: http://www.telegraph.co.uk/sport/othersports/athletics/6158424/ Caster-Semenyas-gender-test-results-force-IAAF-to-call-in- outside-help.html (accessed 5 Oct 2009). 2. National Examiner. IAAF responsible for prejudice athlete Caster Semenya facing. http://www.examiner.com/x-16496-Christian- Pop-Culture-Examiner~y2009m8d25-IAAF-responsible-for- prejudice-athlete-Caster-Semenya-faces (accessed 5 Oct 2009). DOI: 10.3399/bjgp09X472962 work_bkywyshlfzgcldfxu2jtpwqclq ---- Tilburg University Understanding the market for justice Barendrecht, J.M. Publication date: 2009 Document Version Early version, also known as pre-print Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): Barendrecht, J. M. (2009). Understanding the market for justice. (TISCO Working Paper Series; Vol. 009/2009). Tilburg Institute for Interdisciplinary Studies of Civil Law and Conflict Resolution Systems (TISCO). http://ssrn.com/abstract=1416841 General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal ? Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 06. apr. 2021 https://research.tilburguniversity.edu/en/publications/753479af-6d56-4cd0-8cb0-f43d27f27026 http://ssrn.com/abstract=1416841 ��� � TISCO WORKING PAPER SERIES ON CIVIL LAW AND CONFLICT RESOLUTION SYSTEMS Understanding the Market for Justice Maurits Barendrecht Tilburg University, Tilburg Institute for Interdisciplinary Studies of Civil Law and Conflict Resolution Systems (TISCO), International Victimology Institute Tilburg (Intervict), Tilburg Law and Economics Centre (Tilec); Hague Institute for the Internationalisation of Law (HiiL) j.m.barendrecht@uvt.nl TISCO Working Paper Series on Civil Law and Conflict Resolution Systems No. 006/2009 June 9, 2009, Version: 1.0 & Tilburg University Legal Studies Working Paper No. 009/2009 This paper can be downloaded without charge from the Social Science Research Network Electronic Paper Collection http://ssrn.com/abstract=1416841 ��� � Maurits Barendrecht1 Understanding the Market for Justice Abstract If justice is so dearly needed, why does it not emerge spontaneously? Socio-legal research shows how people shop for justice. They approach friends, advisers, lawyers, mediators, suppliers of legal information, local authorities, community leaders, priests, imams, arbiters, or judges in order to obtain redress in situations of conflict. From the perspective of clients, law is probably not so much a system of procedures in which they face barriers to access, but a variety of options on a market for justice services. In this paper, five types of justice services are distinguished. Whether these services are affordable for clients and sustainable to supply, depends on the costs of production and on the transaction costs of making them available. Investigating the sources of transaction costs for each of these justice services improves our understanding of the legal system. This perspective explains why ADR has hardly succeeded in attracting clients, lawyer services are unlikely to become a commodity, norms for distributive issues are often lacking, and courts have trouble to orient themselves on the needs of their customers. It also indicates which type of policies governments and civil society can consider if they wish to improve access to justice. 1 Helpful comments on an earlier version were provided by Martin Gramatikov, Machteld de Hoon, Jan Smits, Jin Ho Verdonschot, Ben Vollaard, and workshop participants at the Hague Institute for Internationalization of the Law (17 april 2008) and Amsterdam Centre for Law and Economics (18 april 2008). ��� � Table of Contents I.� SHOPPING FOR JUSTICE .................................................................................................................................3� II.� THE MARKET FOR JUSTICE ......................................................................................................................5� A.� ACCESS TO JUSTICE ..............................................................................................................................................5� B.� DEMAND: JUSTICE NEEDS ....................................................................................................................................5� C.� FORMAL AND INFORMAL SUPPLY.........................................................................................................................6� D.� ANALYZING THE MARKET FOR JUSTICE ...............................................................................................................7� III.� APPROACH.....................................................................................................................................................10� A.� FIVE DISPUTE RESOLUTION TASKS ....................................................................................................................10� B.� THE PERSPECTIVE OF TRANSACTION COSTS ......................................................................................................10� IV.� TRANSACTION COSTS ON JUSTICE MARKETS .................................................................................12� A.� SELLING SERVICES TO ENEMIES .........................................................................................................................12� 1.� Basic Technology...........................................................................................................................................12� 2.� Transaction Costs of Meeting........................................................................................................................13� 3.� Consequences: Advice, Patronage and Demand for Checks and Balances .................................................14� B.� THE MARKET FOR NEGOTIATION ASSISTANCE ..................................................................................................16� 1.� Basic Technology...........................................................................................................................................16� 2.� Conflict Management Expertise as Public Good and Experience Good ......................................................16� C.� SUPPLYING INFORMATION ABOUT FAIR SOLUTIONS ..........................................................................................17� 1.� Basic Technology...........................................................................................................................................17� 2.� Objective Criteria for Distributive Issues as a Public Good and Experience Good ....................................18� 3.� Consequences: Business Models for Selling Legal Information...................................................................19� D.� DELIVERING THE OPTION OF A NEUTRAL DECISION ..........................................................................................19� 1.� Basic Technology...........................................................................................................................................19� 2.� Buying a Neutral Intervention: A Troublesome Transaction........................................................................20� 3.� Consequences: Access to Neutrals is Unavailable or Unreliable ................................................................21� E.� MAKING ARRANGEMENTS EXPLICIT AND ENFORCEMENT .................................................................................22� 1.� Basic Technology...........................................................................................................................................22� 2.� Transaction Costs of Services that Stabilize Relationships ..........................................................................22� 3.� Consequences: Stabilization Difficult to Obtain for People with Limited Resources ..................................23� F.� COMPLEMENTARITIES ........................................................................................................................................24� 1.� Connectedness between Dispute Services .....................................................................................................24� 2.� Integrated Services ........................................................................................................................................24� V.� CONCLUSIONS ..................................................................................................................................................25� I. Shopping for Justice In Ndirande, a township near Blantyre, the second city of Malawi, men are dying of aids. Their wives know that they will not only lose their husband, but may also become victim to ‘property grabbing.’ The man’s family takes possession of the house and other valuable assets. The wife is sent away, sometimes back to the village where she was born. Quite common in African countries, this practice has some basis in customary laws. Exclusive inheritance through the male line prevents that land becomes divided in ever smaller portions, not sustainable as a farm. In Ndirande, however, women take action against this injustice. They ask advice from friends, try to convince the local leaders to intervene, look for legal aid, and in one case, a victim in Ndirande even succeeded in bringing the case before a formal court (Vossen and Knapen 2009). ��� � Ndirande’s women try what most people do if they need protection in relationships to other people: they shop for justice.2 Legal needs surveys (Genn and Beinart 1999; Johnsen 1999; Genn and Paterson 2001; Pleasence, Buck et al. 2004; Coumarelos, Wei et al. 2006; Currie 2007) and anthropological studies give an impression how they walk away from the conflict, talk, give in, and settle, but also ask help from the police, complain with local authorities, go to the press, organize themselves into groups who can put pressure on the powerful, or find their way to the myriads of priests, imams, commissions, councils, and informal courts that mediate disputes and coax parties into solutions. Once we see justice as a service delivered to people by their peers, the issue of access to justice can be analyzed in similar ways as access to other valuable goods. “Shopping for justice” does not sound too respectful, but it may be an appropriate term, because access is obtained through what economists would call transactions. People address other people and ask them for advice or to exert influence on the other party. Often the suppliers of justice services will expect something in return: a fee, recognition as a leader, or some other favor. Whether justice services will reach the client, first depends on the costs of production. The hours a friend, a lawyer or a judge invests in assisting the client, are one example of production costs. Legal norms have to be produced as well, because information has to be collected, agreement on the rules has to be reached, and norms have to be written down. In this paper, we will mainly focus on a second type of costs: transaction costs. As consumers, clients have to search for suitable justice services. Ideally, they would compare the expected costs (price) and effectiveness of interventions. This search process can be costly, because information about prices and the quality of justice services is hard to obtain. Once lawyers are hired, clients have to monitor them, so that they do what they promised. Even friends or judges will not automatically serve their clients well. Transaction costs are costs of making justice services work. Access to justice is often insufficient. In our terms, this means that no adequate justice services are available. If justice services are not affordable for clients or not sustainable to deliver for suppliers, the production costs may be too high in relation to the value added by the service, or the costs of concluding an adequate transaction may be prohibitive. In this paper, we assume that justice goods are not particularly costly to produce (although we acknowledge that there are some notable exceptions). We focus on the mechanisms by which justice services are delivered and investigate where transaction costs are located. We thus look for explanations why markets do not succeed to deliver justice to those who need it. That markets are not capable of delivering adequate justice will be unsurprising for most readers. They know justice is a matter for states. But what exactly is the source of these problems? This has hardly been investigated yet. Understanding the sources of transaction costs may help us to understand why some people have difficulties in obtaining access to justice. It may also point the way towards interventions that increase access to justice. Section II links the approach of this paper to the existing literature on access to justice and justice markets. In Section III, the approach is explained more in detail. Five types of justice services are distinguised, that each have their own characteristics. These services help disputants to (1) meet in order to seek a cooperative solution, (2) communicate and negotiate, (3) distribute gains and losses fairly, (4) decide on outcomes, and (5) stabilize their relationships. Then follows a brief introduction in transaction cost theory. Section IV investigates the sources of transaction costs associated with the 2 Rev. Alan Sharpton organized marches in shopping districts in order to protest against injustice under this name. We use shopping for justice as a description of the transactions that plaintiffs have to conclude if they want to obtain fair solutions for their conflicts. ��� � five types of services, as well as additional costs caused by the fact that these five dispute services have to work in concert. Section V concludes and takes a quick look at policy implications. II. The Market for Justice A. Access to Justice Whether people can actually obtain a fair and just solution for their conflicts, is known as the problem of access to justice. Access to justice is mostly studied from the point of view of the sociologist: descriptive and without a shared theoretical perspective. Implied in the term access to justice is a perspective of justice as a state of affairs – an organization with lawyers, courts and legislation – to which citizens have access. Many studies describe how people lack access, because they face “barriers to justice.” These studies suggest reforms that may increase access to justice. The literature distinguishes five waves of access to justice reforms: supplying legal aid, public interest litigation, alternative dispute resolution, opening up the market for legal services, and better regulation of the legal profession (Cappeletti and Garth 1978; Parker 1999). As yet, there is no overarching theory integrating these approaches, nor a clear link to the related topics of civil procedure reform (Tyler 1997; Zuckerman, Chiarloni et al. 1999; Bone 2008; Klement and Neeman 2009) and tort reform (Currie and MacLeod 2008). The practical impact of access to justice reform efforts seems to be limited (Rhode 2004). Alternative dispute resolution, for instance, is much hyped, but little used, and it hardly helps to cut the costs of litigation (Hensler 2002; Wissler 2004). Deregulation of the legal profession does not go much further than allowing lawyers to advertise their services or to work together in multidisciplinary practices. Recently, the attention has shifted to bottom up perspectives, particularly in the context of law and development. What can people do themselves to solve their legal problems? How can they be empowered to cope with disputes in their own environment? What do they need from the state? Mediation, with its methods to facilitate negotiation and problem solving between the parties, is one trigger for this. Another one is the growing consensus that top down legal reform, where laws and courts are implemented from above, is not very effective in establishing the rule of law. Most analysts of law and development therefore have started to look at bottom up processes for making the legal system more accessible (Jensen 2002; Carothers 2006). Departing from legal needs and empowering people to serve their own needs are the mantras of today (Golub 2003; Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor 2008). These bottom up approaches are by their nature more market-oriented, so they invite a more thorough analysis of the economy of processes for accessing the legal system (including informal justice systems). The search for lower cost and bottom-up solutions to the problem of access to justice is a venture we referred to as microjustice, This term was created because the mechanisms for delivering justice in an affordable and sustainable manner are likely to resemble the ways in which microcredit, microinsurance, and other microservices can be delivered to the poor (Barendrecht and Van Nispen 2008). Developing microjustice requires focusing on the most urgent justice needs (Barendrecht, Kamminga et al. 2008), the five essential tasks of a dispute system (Barendrecht 2008), the most effective ways to serve those needs through developing adequate justice services (usually by producing dispute resolution services locally (Barendrecht 2009)), and lowering the transaction costs of delivering these services (this paper). B. Demand: Justice Needs At the demand side, people are most active in trying to get access to justice in situations of conflict. Research suggests three types of relationships in which they are looking for dispute resolution services (Barendrecht 2008; Barendrecht, Kamminga et al. 2008). Personal security presents the most urgent category of problems. Threats may come from outside the community where a person ��� � lives: robbing, looting, maybe even supported by factions in governments. In these situations, people seek basic protection of their human rights. Such protection against violence, unlawful taking of property, and unlawful detention is needed in relationships with outsiders and with the state. The second type evolves from long term relationships with substantial specific investments, such as family, work, land use, neighbor, and business relationships. Institutional economists have identified the reasons behind this need for protection. In these relationships, parties have to cope with changes in circumstances, preferences, and abilities, which they cannot predict, so their contracts are incomplete. Adaptation to change through negotiation is a necessity, but this takes place in a situation of bilateral monopoly. The parties are dependent on each other, because they invested in the relationship, and cannot walk away from it without leaving these investments behind. Here, some type of dispute resolution is part of the governance structure needed to adapt to these changes, hence the term trilateral governance (Williamson 1987; Nooteboom 1992; Barendrecht 2008; Robson and Skaperdas 2008). Disputes in this category have private law as their basis, with doctrines such as unforeseen circumstances, mistake and impossibility to perform (Chakravarty, MacLeod et al. 2008). Examples of disputes that arise in this context are property conflicts within a community, inheritance issues, problems between landlord and tenant, divorce, neighbor conflict and termination of a long term cooperation in work or business. A third category of conflicts emerges from arms length relationships between buyers and sellers, or from obligations of the bureaucracy to its citizens. Here, the dispute resolution process typically begins as a complaint about conduct that falls short of what the plaintiff may expect. Legal dispute resolution in this area is largely a matter of investigating what the plaintiff could expect (interpretation of contracts and regulation), how the defendant contributed to these expectations by giving or withholding information (duties to inform, which can come from different legal sources), and whether the defendant delivered goods or behavior that live up to the legitimate expectations of the plaintiff. The way the defendant reacted to the initial problem and the ensuing communication is another point of attention. Fact-finding regarding quality of goods and finding proof regarding the actual behavior of the defendant may be necessary here as well. The dispute processes regarding these issues may fit in legal categories such as civil procedure, criminal procedure, or administrative procedure. Demand for justice services is not always related to an actual conflict. In order to prevent conflict, and to make relationships work, people may find it useful to make explicit what they can expect from each other in the future. They thus agree on rules of conduct and write contracts. They may also delineate property rights, for instance by registering them. Because these ‘stabilization-services’ are also needed after a conflict is resolved, we will consider them part of the services that are needed in settings of conflict (see Section IVE). C. Formal and Informal Supply Exploration of the supply side suggests that justice services do not always meet this demand. Lawyers have a reputation of being costly; courts of being slow and at times unpredictable. For most relationships and disputes between individuals, or with small businesses as the clients, the formal legal system is expensive to use in comparison to the value at stake (see the World Bank "Doing Business" reports and Zuckerman, Chiarloni et al. 1999). For the majority of people in developing economies, this is true in particular. Access to justice through police, lawyers and courts is outside their reach for protection of property, employment problems, family issues, neighborhood conflict and disputes regarding their businesses. According to the Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor, 4 billion people can only hope that some informal way of getting justice is around when a conflict arises (Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor 2008). However, justice services are not only provided by the formal system. They emerge spontaneously in family disputes, where brothers and sisters intervene, and mothers and fathers provide a back up. Rural communities and townships develop their informal justice systems (Wojkowska 2006). Even in ��� � refugee camps, where many tense people live together closely, informal dispute systems arise within weeks. A more realistic picture is thus that people seeking fair solutions look for justice wherever it is on offer. Employees contact people in the company who support them if they have a conflict with their immediate boss. If there is a formal complaint procedure, they may use it. A company mediation scheme, an external commission that hears employee complaints, or a court specializing in labor matters may also be available. One frequently used avenue is that disputants ask local leaders to intervene. In Bulgaria, for instance, around 30% of the respondents to a legal needs survey told they addressed the local authorities for conflicts with other citizens, although these may have no formal jurisdiction (Gramatikov 2008). In many countries majors of towns hear citizens with complaints about other people, and in developing economies local leaders are often the first avenue for redress (Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor 2008). From the perspective of plaintiffs that is understandable: these leaders are accessible at low cost, and their interventions may be quite effective. If they do not intervene in a satisfactory way, the shopping goes on. Even in the Netherlands, a country that scores high on every rule of law index, the police, social workers, trade unions, private dispute resolution commissions and consumer organizations deal with at least as big a share of disputes as lawyers and courts (Van Velthoven and Ter Voert 2004). To what extent these formal and informal dispute services fulfill the needs of their clients, is unsure, because they are hard to monitor and to assess. But there is abundant evidence that access to justice, either through the formal legal system or through these informal arrangements, is insufficient in many places and in many situations (Parker 1999; Anderson 2003; Rhode 2004; Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor 2008). Legal needs surveys show that even in developed countries around 45% of the people reporting a conflict with subtantial impact on their lives do not seek access to justice – “lumping it” in the jargon – or stop their attempts. Sometimes the problem goes away, or becomes less important over time, but often the expected costs and trouble of pursuing the matter are too high for them. About 45% of disputes make it into a settlement, but this is not always experienced as a fair outcome (Van Velthoven and Ter Voert 2004). Although bias in perception of fairness is one explanation for this, it is also likely that many people accept an unsatisfactory settlement because the costs of pursuing the matter would be too high. Many people addressing the formal justice system express dissatisfaction: they feel that lawyers and courts do not acknowledge what they find important, experience a loss of control, and complain about unexpected costs (Relis 2002). If the costs of production of justice would be high, this would explain why many people cannot satisfy their justice needs. However, in most disputes basic negotiation processes and third party interventions can provide reasonably fair solutions at low costs. A skilled mediator or lower court judge will be able to settle most family, employment, and neighbor disputes in a few hours. The technologies of providing justice are not prohibitively expensive (Barendrecht 2009). But there are some exceptions: inducing powerful people to cooperate can be quite costly. Inflicting punishment on perpetrators may have high costs as well (Barendrecht 2009). Another indication that justice services do not reach the clients by the virtuous operation of the market alone is of course that they are often delivered by the state. Providing legislation and court services are classical tasks of governments. D. Analyzing the Market for Justice If justice services are valuable, not inherently costly, but still difficult to deliver, and the state has an active role, this suggests that the market for justice has substantial imperfections. No comprehensive analysis of the market for justice exists as yet. But several strands of literature contribute to our understanding of the ways justice is obtained. This paper builds on these bodies of knowledge. � � � An intuitive approach would probably distinguish two basic forms of justice services. Plaintiffs either go to advisers: friends, lawyers, or others who assist them to handle the process. Or they go to persons who can influence the other party: village elders, religious authorities, and judges. Lawyers and courts fit these two categories, and indeed the way these services are delivered have been studied to some extent. The literature on the market for legal services rendered by lawyers tends to frame legal services as similar to other professional services. A transaction cost problem discussed in this context is the asymmetry of information between lawyer and client (Stephen 2006). Another issue derives from the way the customer can judge the value of legal servicec. Before the service has been provided the client is unable to judge whether what was supplied was appropriate, and even afterwards establishing the added value of the lawyer is problematic. The term credence good has been used to describe this situation. If clients cannot distinguish good legal services from mediocre or bad ones, the better value but high cost services can be driven out by the bad quality and lower cost services. This adverse selection problem, described by Akerlof as the market for lemons in relation to second hand cars, may be addressed by regulating entry to the market by setting quality standards (Akerlof 1970; Stephen 2006). Another problem is that of moral hazard, where the lawyer diagnoses the problem and advises a service that is profitable for him, but not adequate for the client (Stephen 2006). Regulation of the legal profession is usually self-regulation by the bar, so there is the possibility of regulation that is more in favor of the profession than of the consumer. The literature concludes that legal services are regulated too heavily, resulting in limited market entry and innovation, as well as costs that are higher than necessary (Stephen and Love 1999; Hadfield 2000; Baarsma, Felsö et al. 2008). Some analysts see commercial lawyers and other legal professionals as a closed shop, with a common interest to keep the law complex (Hadfield 2000; Hadfield 2008). Others are far more optimistic and believe that a trend towards commoditization of legal services and ever lower prices is inevitable (Susskind 2008). Access to courts is mainly been studied by researchers with a legal background, but the literature on the efficiency of court services is growing. The incentives on courts have been analyzed theoretically (Posner 1993; Cabrillo and Fitzpatrick 2008). Empirical studies have shown that judges mainly answer to higher courts, which they tend to depend on for their career perspectives (Schneider 2005). Another piece of helpful literature evaluates justice sector reform efforts in third world countries (López de Silanes 2002; Hammergren 2007). This line or research tends to conclude that inadequate incentives and unnecessarily complex procedures are the main causes of underperformance of courts (Botero, La Porta et al. 2003). Increased funding by itself is unlikely to lead to better performance. Incentive-oriented reforms that seek to increase accountability, competition, and choice seem to be the most effective in tackling the problem (López de Silanes 2002; Botero, La Porta et al. 2003). Evaluation and monitoring, as well as opening up the reform efforts and the dispute system itself to non-lawyers, is thought to be necessary as well (López de Silanes 2002; Hammergren 2007). Linking informal dispute systems to formal systems should take place through recognition of the procedures and results of informal systems, with targeted constraints, and if necessary improving them within the formal system (Buscaglia and Stephan 2005; Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor 2008). The usual analysis in terms of two types of services – lawyer-like and court-like – is incomplete, however. It ignores some important properties of justice markets that have to be integrated in the analysis. First, court services and the services of lawyers are usually rendered to two parties who interact in a conflict. The disputants negotiate in the shadow of a court intervention. An extensive literature on these settlement negotiations exists (Tullock 1980; Pinkley, Neale et al. 1994; Huang 2007; Korobkin and Doherty 2007; Daughety and Reinganum 2008). The resulting trilateral relationship between opponents and a third party complicates justice transactions with courts or other neutrals, as we will � � � see. In the relationship between the client and his lawyer, the interaction with the other party also makes life more difficult. For the client it is harder to monitor a lawyer than another professional services provider, because the amount of work the lawyer does depends on reactions of the opponent, which may be triggered by the lawyer himself. The literature shows how the parties may become trapped in an arms race, fuelled by the interests of the lawyers, and try to outspend each other in attempts to convince the court to give a decision in their favor (Tullock 1980; Daughety and Reinganum 2008). Secondly, the interaction between the parties is influenced by rules. Negotiations in disputes take place in the shadow of the law (Mnookin and Kornhauser 1978; Cooter, Marks et al. 1982). Norms and other objective criteria inform the parties about outcomes deemed to be fair, particularly for distributive issues. The supply of these norms to the clients can be seen as a transaction in itself. There is adequate academic literature about the thesis that common law systems are more likely to produce efficient norms than civil law, tending to conclude that both legal traditions will evolve towards a mixed system with courts and legislators as complementing producers of law (Djankov, La Porta et al. 2003; Gennaioli and Shleifer 2007; Ponzetto and Fernandez 2008). The broader question of how norms are produced has been studied less intensively (Posner and Rasmusen 1999), and seldom through the lens of the demand for norms by clients and supply by private parties or government agents (Hadfield 2004; Hadfield and Talley 2006; Barendrecht and Verdonschot 2008). Moreover, the delivery of information about these norms may be a problem in itself, as knowledge about useful norms may be accessible to the legal profession, but not by the clients who need the norms. Third, the existing literature on markets for legal services tends to ignore the costs of access to justice that are not related to hiring a lawyer. Economists usually assume that property rights and contract enforcement exist and are guaranteed by the state at no cost. Only a few of them have discussed the accessibility of property rights as a problem of supply and demand. Hernando de Soto famously investigated the costs and benefits of property rights registrations in Peru and other developing countries (De Soto 2000). Besides costs of lawyers and court fees, the costs of delay and the emotional costs of a dispute resolution procedure can be substantial. Another important category of costs is the time spent. Collecting information about the facts, documenting this information, travel, waiting, searching for expertise, settlement negotiations, and attending hearings by neutrals can be time consuming affairs (see Gramatikov 2008 for a review of the literature). Fourth, the usual analysis of legal services tends to consider them as one type of service (Stephen and Love 1999; Stephen 2006; Baarsma, Felsö et al. 2008; Susskind 2008). In this paper we break down services by lawyers, who often lead their clients through several steps in the dispute resolution process, into constituent parts: assistance with negotiation, informing about norms, helping to access courts, and supplying formats for relationships (contracts, property rights). As we will see, these services each have their own characteristics, with different sources of transaction costs. Finally, and most importantly, we will relax the implied assumption that a formal legal system with courts and laws is present. In a more realistic description of the context for dispute resolution, neutral dispute services can also be delivered by private parties, such as local leaders, arbiters, or mediators. Norms can be developed by legislators and courts, but also emerge as social norms, or be designed by private actors. Enforcement of judgments can take place through agents of the state, but also by providers of enforcement services such as bailiffs, or by the threat of exclusion from a community if a defendant does not comply (Dixit 2004; Greif 2006). Extending the literature on governance institutions (Dixit 2009), we will analyze the specific governance transactions people conclude if they want to be protected and the costs of these transactions. ���� � III. Approach A. Five Dispute Resolution Tasks Let us assume a plaintiff, who wants to be protected in a relationship to another person, the defendant, from which he is dependent. The plaintiff wants a change in the status quo in the direction of a fair and just outcome of the dispute – actually he probably would not mind doing slightly better than fair, but that does not change the analysis in any significant way. The defendant, who is satisfied with the situation as it is, does not immediately give in to the demands of the plaintiff. The defendant may want to change the status quo as well, and in this respect he has to be considered as a plaintiff. Plaintiffs try to communicate and negotiate with the defendant and to influence him. He asks suppliers of justice to assist him in these processes. From the literature on dispute system design (Ury, Brett et al. 1988; Costantino and Sickles Merchant 1996; Shariff 2003; Bingham 2008; Bordone 2008) and from the practice of formal (legal) and informal dispute systems, a model of five distinct disputkojl;ing tasks can be derived (see table 1). These are the necessary and sufficient elements of a dispute system (Barendrecht 2008). For each of the five elements of a dispute system, there are basic technologies for delivery. Services that support these tasks make use of these basic technologies and can be delivered to the plaintiff. Task Description Basic Technology for Justice services 1. Meet Centralized forum for information processing Make costs and benefits of participation for defendant higher than costs and benefits of fighting, appropriation, or avoiding 2. Talk Communication and negotiation Support integrative negotiation (interest based) 3. Share Distributing value fairly Supply information about fair shares (sharing rules, objective criteria) 4. Decide Decision making procedure Make option of a neutral decision available (at low cost) 5. Stabilize Transparency and compliance Supply tools to make arrangements explicit; Make costs and benefits of compliance higher than those of non- compliance Table 2 Necessary and Sufficient Elements of a Dispute System with Basic Technologies for Delivery (Barendrecht 2008). To start with, the plaintiff and the persons assisting him need to induce the defendant to cooperate. If the defendant can ignore the plaintiff, or fight his way out of the conflict, justice cannot be achieved. Next, the plaintiff and the defendant have to communicate and negotiate, looking for a solution that fits their interests in the best possible ways. Lawyers, mediators, or other helpers with negotiation skills can assist here. Besides trying to create value by finding a win-win solution, the parties usually have to bargain in order to distribute value. Legal rules and social norms can be supplied, thus helping the parties to settle these distributive issues. If they do not agree, a third party helps them to decide: a private adjudicator or a court. They also need settlement contracts, or other means to make the future arrangements explicit. Enforcement is a matter of making it attractive for the other party to live up to the outcome, and here again the plaintiff may be assisted by suppliers of justice services. These are the types of justice transactions plaintiffs need to close. We will consider transactions concluded with private parties, as well as the transactions that take place with persons or organizations that are part of the government: police, judges, or officials who register property rights and other instruments to make relationships transparent. It is not customary to see the relationship between the client and these persons as a contract, but the client certainly has a direct interest that these persons serve him well. For the client, the problem is again how he can find the right provider of the service, determine the most helpful service, and monitor the performance of these government agents. This is the perspective of transaction costs. B. The Perspective of Transaction Costs Transaction costs are the costs of undertaking a transaction. Transaction costs include search and information costs, as well as bargaining costs. Organizations involved in the transaction also make incur costs of setting up and running the organization. In addition, there are the monitoring and ���� � enforcement costs of implementing a transaction (Rao 2003). In the case of delivery of justice, transaction costs are likely to include the costs of searching for the right type of services, the costs of bargaining with lawyers, the costs of addressing courts, as well as the costs of monitoring courts, lawyers, and other suppliers of justice services. Moreover, transaction costs cover ‘the costs of running the economic system.’ These include the costs of arrangements that deal with externalities and other types of market failure (Williamson 1981; Rao 2003). The market for dispute resolution services, for instance, may have to cope with information asymmetry, because lawyers know more about the services to be delivered than their clients (Stephen and Love 1999; Baarsma, Felsö et al. 2008). If governments step in to perform certain tasks, they also generate costs, and their activities may influence the abilities of markets to perform these tasks efficiently. Moreover, government organizations, such as courts, have to be run as well, and may struggle to do so efficiently, for reasons that can be brought under the heading of government failure. The bottom line is that each way of organizing transactions, through the market or via governments, has its price (Williamson 1999). Gradually, governance structures will develop that minimize these costs (Dixit 2009). Five dimensions of transactions are often mentioned that strongly influence transaction costs (Milgrom and Roberts 1992). These are: 1. The specificity of the investments required. If a task is performed with the needs of one particular customer in mind, it may be that the investments cannot be made productive for other clients, so the supplier becomes dependent on this particular customer. Thus, a need for protection against early termination or renegotiation of contract terms arises. Legal services indeed tend to be specially made, fitting the circumstances of the individual case. 2. The frequency of similar transactions and the duration of them. Repeated interactions, or long term relationships, need less governance, because understandings can develop over time and the parties have incentives to take each others’ interests into account because they expect future gains from the relationship. Most clients of dispute services make use of them only once, though. 3. Uncertainty and complexity. Both of these elements make it more difficult to be explicit about what should be done to make the transaction happen. Interventions in disputes can be complex, legally, or in terms of conflict management techniques, and the reactions of the other party can cause a considerable amount of uncertainty. 4. Difficulty of performance measurement. Milgrom and Roberts describe the difficulties of assessing whether a divorce lawyer has done his job, as the client has little means of ascertain whether the negotiated deal is a good one, or whether another lawyer would have been able to negotiate a better deal (Milgrom and Roberts 1992). 5. Connectedness to other transactions. Software designers have to coordinate their efforts with those of the hardware producers on which the software will run, as well as with the suppliers of the operating systems. As we will see, the services of lawyers, mediators, courts and legislators are also connected in many ways. The transaction costs approach has more or less replaced the better known analysis, which uses the concept of market failure in order to establish where governments should step in. Since ideal markets do not exist, and governments may not be able to remedy market failure in a way that lowers aggregate transaction costs, the existence of market failure is not sufficient to warrant an intervention. Still, common categories of market failure can help to identify sources of transaction costs. Stiglitz, in his handbook of Economics of the Public Sector, mentions six categories of market failure (Stiglitz 2000): • Occurrence of imperfect competition from monopolies, cartels, or monopolistic competition • Public goods • Externalities (including network effects) ���� � • Incomplete markets (innovation, asymmetries of information, enforcement costs, adverse selection, complementary markets) • Information failures (asymmetric information, insufficient production of information because of its public good character) • Macro-economic distortions (unemployment, inflation, disequilibrium) Likewise, he distinguishes four reasons for government failure (Stiglitz 2000): • Limited information • Limited control over private market response • Limited control over bureaucracy (insufficient incentives) • Limitations imposed by the political process Transaction cost economics has not yet developed into a hard science. Measuring transaction costs is difficult. Empirical research generally confirms the central tenets of transaction cost economics, like the tendency towards governance structures with lower transaction costs, but it is not conducted on a large scale (David and Han 2004; Macher and Richman 2008). For a particular transaction, it is possible to establish the likely sources of transaction costs, however. The five dimensions of transactions that usually influence the level of transaction costs can be a basis for this assessment. Until now, the transaction costs perspective has not yet been systematically applied to transactions delivering justice. Husted and Folger have suggested that governance structures are in essence conflict resolution mechanisms, and that considerations regarding the fairness of outcomes, as well as interactional justice, influence the level of transaction costs (Husted and Folger 2004). This fits in the paradigm that third party governance structures are necessary in certain transactions, in particular where relation specific investments are high (Williamson 1981; Dixit 2009). Institutional economists compare governance structures and assume that they tend towards institutions with lower transaction costs, whereas property rights theorists look at the difficulties of delineating property rights in an efficient way (Kim and Mahoney 2005). Although some writers touched on the issue (Libecap 1989; Rapaczynski 1996; Kim and Mahoney 2005; Robson and Skaperdas 2008), the existing literature on transaction cost economics does hardly cover the (second order) problem of transacting with a third party who delivers governance to the two participants in the original transaction. In this paper, we look at these second order transactions that we refer to as justice transactions. IV. Transaction Costs on Justice Markets For each of the five justice services, we will now investigate the likely size and sources of transaction costs. These costs depend on the kind of transactions that are needed. So we first go back to the basic technology for delivering each of the dispute resolution services that the plaintiff needs and give examples of suppliers of these services. Then we identify the likely sources of transaction costs, and the way justice markets respond to these costs. A. Selling Services to Enemies 1. Basic Technology Coping with conflict cooperatively requires interaction between parties. The defendant has to come to the telephone, the negotiation table, or the court-room. Some form of centralized information processing is necessary (Shariff 2003). So the first thing that the plaintiff needs, is a meeting place where the defendant is present and willing to communicate about the conflict. The basic technology for letting the parties meet is simple. The costs and benefits of participation to cooperative dispute resolution for both parties have to be higher than those of alternatives ways to cope with the conflict. For the plaintiff, this task requires that he makes it more attractive for the ���� � defendant to meet him, than to ignore the conflict, or to fight him in whatever way and with whatever weapons. There are many ways to achieve this for the plaintiff, that can be offered as a service to him. For instance, a meeting place can be made attractive for the defendant by being close and safe. If the defendant predicts that the interaction that will take place will lead to creative solutions to the problems of the parties, the expected value of going to the meeting place will be higher for him. Task Best Practices for Dispute Services/Transactions Possible Providers of Services 1. Meet - Local meeting places or other channels of communication - Pre-mediation skills - Social norms to solve conflicts cooperatively - Enhance incentives that link to reputation of defendants to solve conflicts cooperatively - Option of default judgment - First line legal aid - Friends and advisers - Community leaders - Mediators - Courts Table 3 Best Practices for Facilitating the Dispute System Task of Meeting and Service Providers (adapted from Barendrecht 2009) In case both the defendant and the plaintiff want a change in the status quo, both have something to gain from the meeting, and it will be relatively easy to induce them to do so. Inducing the defendant to meet is more problematic if the defendant expects an outcome that will make him worse off. A defendant may fear that he has to pay a substantial amount of money as compensation, or even has to undergo some form of punishment. In such cases, the plaintiff will need more help from others to create a context in which the defendant will still have incentives to participate in a cooperative process. If the defendant cares for his reputation, it may help if the plaintiff can assemble a larger group of people who are important to the defendant. If the defendant has little to loose, the threat of punishment, or even forced cooperation, may be needed. Then the plaintiff needs help from the police, or another service that makes the defendant comply. 2. Transaction Costs of Meeting Interaction is needed for a fair solution of a conflict, but getting two disputants in one room is hard. Evidence of this transaction cost problem is everywhere around us. A husband and wife are not finding a way to talk about their deteriorating relationship, and eventually about their divorce. Before two companies and their lawyers meet to negotiate, many letters and telephone calls have to be exchanged. Even wars may start without any real attempt at negotiation, mediation, or arbitration (perhaps the best example being World War I, where Nicholas II the Tsar did not even suggest to meet his nephew Kaiser Wilhelm II in The Hague’s newly opened Peace Palace, although having an International Court of Justice to prevent war had been the Tsar’s idea). More generally, it is hard to agree about a way to deal with a conflict, even if both parties are likely to gain from cooperative dispute resolution. The technical term for this is an ex post dispute agreements, where the parties already in conflict agree to a specific procedure, or a particular person who will decide on their issues. Such agreements are rare (Shavell 1995; Barendrecht and De Vries 2006). Where a defendant is offered the option of mediation, rejection rates are high (Moore 2003). Mediation services are widely available all over the world, but the number of mediations actually taking place is very disappointing. In fact, very few registered mediators can make a living from it (Velikonja 2009). On a mediation summit in 2008 organized by the ABA in The Hague, one speaker estimated the size of the market for mediation in the US at $500 million, which is equal to the turnover of the 50th largest US law firm. Most mediation is court-annexed, and takes place late in the procedure, when most legal costs have already been spent (Stipanowich 2004). Arbitration institutes have similar trouble attracting sufficient clients. Once the employment conflict is there, binding arbitration is hardly ever agreed on. Difficulties of concluding ex post dispute agreements do not only occur if alternative dispute resolution is proposed. Most legal systems allow agreements over the way to conduct a legal procedure. Such ���� � agreements would be very effective tools to diminish legal costs, and to tailor the procedure to the needs of the litigants. But they hardly occur (Barendrecht and De Vries 2006). In actual litigation practice, agreements about the way to conduct court proceedings do not extend beyond very practical arrangements about logistics. What we basically see here, is a dispute about how a dispute should be dealt with. Continued unresolved conflict, or war, is usually a negative sum game and thus undesirable. Agreeing on a dispute resolution process is generally a Pareto improvement for both parties. However, the way the problem will be tackled is very likely to become an issue for bargaining itself. This second order negotiation problem seems to be difficult to solve, for reasons similar to the first order problem. The psychological barriers that impede the resolution of a conflict itself, are also likely to show up when the parties talk about the way to solve the conflict (Barendrecht and De Vries 2006). Reactive devaluation occurs when a disputant distrusts an opponent’s proposal regarding a suitable dispute resolution procedure (Ross 1995). Over-optimism may cause him to underestimate the impact of the dispute, or the value of his outside options. Loss aversion may cause a defendant to postpone participation in a cooperative procedure if he expects to be required to make concessions (Arrow 1995). At the initial stage of conflict resolution we are talking about, we have to add the effects of negative emotions. Angry, fearful or contemptuous parties are not very likely to make a calm and reasonable decision about the way to resolve a conflict in a cooperative manner (Allred 2005; Van Kleef, De Dreu et al. 2006). Another important category of market failure is probably the possibility that individuals have strategic reasons for not – yet – wanting to deal with the dispute in a cooperative way. While a plaintiff wants fast results, a defendant is better off in the status quo and does not mind a lengthier procedure. One party may fear extensive neutral fact-finding, while the other party expects to gain from the investigation. In essence, this is a bargaining problem where both parties can gain from concluding a transaction, but have to split the gains from trade. Bargaining theory and empirical research show that the risk of impasse is substantial, because the parties obtain better results if they are patient, make extreme offers, commit themselves to making no further offers, try to hide information from the other party, and make efforts to develop alternative ways to serve their interests (Muthoo 1999; Muthoo 2000; Carraro, Marchiori et al. 2006; Korobkin and Doherty 2007). As we have seen, there are also situations where cooperative dispute resolution is not in the interest of the defendant, because he is likely to be worse off. Then the plaintiff may have to rely on others to provide additional incentives on the defendant to cooperate. The costs of the transactions necessary to influence the other party can be quite high, if the defendant is a powerful person. Many people may have to team up before a big company changes an unjust policy. In order to confront a dictator, quite some people have to unite and spokesman have to be found, who take the risk of retaliation, as human rights lawyers know. From the perspective of the individual plaintiff, many transactions have to be coordinated with many people who agree to take some form of action. Having to align many connected transactions is a common source of transaction costs. 3. Consequences: Advice, Patronage and Demand for Checks and Balances The high transaction costs of ex post dispute resolution agreements have important consequences. Clients and justice providers face a difficulty that is uncommon in the economic system. Most goods and services are sold to one buyer, or to a group of persons with similar interests. A mediator, arbiter or judge, on the other hand, has two clients, who are likely not on speaking terms, and with interests that are poorly aligned. Because the two parties cannot easily choose a dispute resolution process together, it is unlikely that they will hire a neutral. Instead, they turn to services they can buy by themselves. Many people in a dispute seek unilateral advice. They go to a friend or a lawyer. For such a decision, the other party is not needed, so the ���� � transaction costs of buying this service are much lower than the costs of buying dispute services jointly with the other party. A lawyer certainly offers valuable services: coaching, advising on options and norms, help with negotiation and with addressing a neutral (Mnookin, Susskind et al. 1999; Mnookin, Peppet et al. 2000). But the presence of an agent may also create new transaction cost problems. Depending on how he is paid, he may have a perverse interest to complicate the dispute instead of helping to solve it. Moreover, if one party hires an adviser, the other tends to hire one too, thus diminishing the value of the lawyer for the first party. An arms race may result (Tullock 1980). Finally, there are now four people who need to be willing to meet and talk, so the coordination problem may become even more complicated to solve. The other common reaction of plaintiffs who want to solve a dispute but cannot find a way to meet the defendant is to address a person who can influence the defendant. Disputes create a market for neutrals that exert power over others. This demand for power is studied under various headings that have a negative connotation to them, such as patronage, clientilism and corruption. The basis is a very common phenomenon, however. People look for parents, bosses, clan leaders and government officials who can help them to get protect their interests in relationships with others (Dixit 2004; Dixit 2009). Asking the powerful for help can be seen as another transaction. The powerful person offers his interventions. The sources of power that shape these interventions are well known. By inflicting sanctions, by offering rewards and by using expert knowledge the powerful can help people to solve their disputes. If they have legitimacy, or act as an example (referent power), they can use this to influence the defendant (French and Raven 2001). For the powerful person the intervention is costly, and he is likely to ask something in return. He may want to be paid in cash, or get support for his causes. Rewards may also come in the form of being seen as a wise and just person, or from the satisfaction of being able to help people with settling their issues. Transactions involving the powerful in disputes are rather complicated in nature. The inputs from the sources of power are very context specific and so are the rewards for the powerful person. The efforts of the powerful person are difficult to monitor. Because power can be used in many ways, from benevolent to malicious, and the plaintiff has little control over the person he has asked to intervene, the outcome remains unsure. The demand for interventions by powerful people thus creates an additional demand for restraints on power. Checks and balances on power become needed. Complexity, high specificity and difficult monitoring all point in the direction of high transaction costs. So the high transaction costs of obtaining justice in the straightforward way of hiring a neutral, lead to extra demand for unilateral advice (lawyers) and to extra demand for interventions by powerful people who can influence others. These transactions in turn lead to very substantial transaction costs. Finally, some plaintiffs are unlikely to succeed in making defendants cooperate. Some defendants have much to loose from solving the disputes in a cooperative way, and some defendants are too powerful. Organizing pressure on these defendants requires extensive coordination between many persons. Even at this introductory stage, before the actual dispute resolution process begins, justice markets already face difficulties. So it is not surprising that the state has become active in the market for justice in order to stimulate cooperative dispute processes. For criminal acts governments provide prosecution services. In civil disputes, the defendant must appear in court in order to discuss the issues, otherwise he will be sanctioned with a default judgment. ���� � B. The Market for Negotiation Assistance 1. Basic Technology Once both parties reach a meeting place, the plaintiff needs to communicate and negotiate with the defendant. Through negotiations, they can try to find Pareto-optimal outcomes for the conflict. The basic technology for finding win-win solutions is one of integrative – or problemsolving – negotiations. Here, the following subprocesses are essential (Walton and McKersie 1965; Fisher, Ury et al. 1991; Lewicki, Saunders et al. 2006): First, the parties have to review and adjust relational conditions to create an environment that promotes communication and information-sharing. After reviewing and adjusting perceptions, the process should focus on interests: the needs, wishes and fears of the disputants. The disputants are advised to take a joint problem-solving approach to the dispute, be creative in developing a number of solutions, and choose a (win-win) solution that best fits the interests of both parties. Task Best Practices for Dispute Services/Transactions Possible Providers of Services 2. Talk - Negotiation assistance (integrative negotiations) - Communication, active listening, questioning techniques - Reframing and adjusting perceptions - Managing emotions and interaction - Improving relationship, recognition, apology, supply of coping skills - Standard format integrative negotiations (identify interests, issues, explore win-win solutions) - Advisers - Lawyers - Mediators (facilitative) - On-line facilities Table 4 Best Practices for Facilitating the Dispute System Task of Talking and Service Providers (adapted from Barendrecht 2009) The plaintiff can buy services that bring integrative negotiation to the table via the market. The skills and practices that support these processes are well described, and made accessible for practitioners (Moffitt, Bordone et al. 2005; Deutsch, Coleman et al. 2006; Oetzel and Ting-Toomey 2006). Facilitating problemsolving negotiations can be done by mediators (Wall, Stark et al. 2001; Moore 2003), by cooperative lawyers (Lande 2005; Lande 2008), or by online dispute resolution facilities (Katsh, Katsh et al. 2001; Braun, Brzostowski et al. 2006; Brett, Olekalns et al. 2007). If the parties learn these techniques, they can also apply them without assistance (Fisher, Ury et al. 1991; Ury 1991). 2. Conflict Management Expertise as Public Good and Experience Good Transactions in which the parties buy these services are relatively easy to close. Assuming the parties have solved the problem of meeting, and have found a way to coordinate their attempts to buy the type of services that can help to solve the dispute, buying conflict management expertise is not very different from buying engineering skills, software expertise, or management advice. The only fundamental problem suppliers of this expertise face, is that they basically sell information. Varian distinguishes three attributes of information goods that make them difficult to bring to the market (Varian 1998; Raban 2007), which also apply to information needed by those seeking access to justice (Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor 2008). Information is often a public good (Stiglitz 1999; Raban 2007). Once it is delivered, the buyer of the information cannot be stopped from using the information for other purposes, or even selling it to others. Because the seller of the information knows this, he has insufficient incentive to produce this information and bring it to the market. Although the value of information about integrative negotiation techniques can be high, it may thus not reach the consumers. Another problem is that people can only tell whether they want to obtain information after they have obtained it. Information is an experience good. Sellers of conflict management information thus have a hard time to convince their buyers to spend money on these goods before they actually get them (Varian 1998). Finally, information products often require a high upfront investment in production costs, whereas the marginal costs of producing and distributing extra copies is close to zero (Varian 1998) ���� � Information sellers have found various ways to cope with these problems, and these are used in the context of dispute resolution services as well. The experience good problem can be overcome by giving people previews of the information, by independent reviewing of the information, or by building reputations for delivering high value information (Varian 1998). Expertise can be sold successfully by packaging it with other services. The professional services literature distinguishes four basic forms of packaging: adding value to information for a specific client, improving client decision-making, enhancing client processes, or improving client skills (Dawson 2005). Professional services firms specializing in engineering, accounting, or medical expertise show how to do this. And legal services have followed. General dispute resolution knowledge can be customized and individualized in relation to the needs of the client. This product differentiation, or versioning (Shapiro and Varian 1998), diminishes the possibility to reuse or to resell it. A lawyer or another dispute resolution professional can also help the client to solve his individual dispute, improving the clients decision making. The client does not have to apply the information to his own problem. He gets tailor-made advice. A next possibility is to run the process for the client. Just as a management consultant can organize the process to form a corporate strategy for the client, a lawyer or a mediator can organize the negotiations for his client. The lawyer may even take the dispute resolution process out of the hands of the client completely, by bringing his case before the court. A fourth business model for selling information is to improve clients skills. This can be done by packaging large chunks of information together. A book, a course, or a website only accessible for members are examples of this model. Here the individualization is left to the clients, who should read the book, or find out for themselves how to apply the skills and best practices to their particular situation. Not every client is likely to be served in the same way by these four business models for selling information. Tailor made advice and services that run the process for the client are easily accessible, but expensive because they are usually provided on a one client to one expert basis. If the expert takes the dispute out of the hands of the client, this is likely to be a costly affair as well, and it is not certain that the client’s interests are served. Clients who cannot afford individualized services have to rely on general information packaged in books or brought to them in workshops or other forms of education. They have to do the individualization themselves, or hope that the information reaches them in other ways. So poor people, who cannot afford individualized professional services, and who may lack the skills to individualize useful general information, are less likely to be reached, a hypothesis that has been confirmed by empirical research (Buck, Pleasence et al. 2008). Commoditization, as it takes place in consumer goods markets, where economies of scale bring goods within reach of ever more consumers, has been predicted for legal services (Susskind 2008). But it is unlikely to occur in the market for dispute resolution services. Until sustainable business models are developed that can bring conflict resolution information to poor clients, dispute resolution skills and knowledge are bound to be a luxury good. C. Supplying Information about Fair Solutions 1. Basic Technology Disputes always include issues over value that has to be distributed. In case of divorce, assets must be divided and care for children allocated to each of the parents. Personal injury claims have to be settled by some amount of money. In many relationships. there is the problem of how to share the work that must be done and the revenues that come from the relationship. Settling distributive issues in conflicts is difficult, because the parties are dependent on each other. They can only settle with this one other party (a bilateral monopoly). The bargaining literature shows �� � � that they often get stuck (Muthoo 1999; Muthoo 2000; Carraro, Marchiori et al. 2006; Korobkin and Doherty 2007). The underlying dynamics are that a disputant does better in distributive issues if he has more patience, makes more extreme offers, commits himself more, has more attractive outside and inside options, and has more information. If both parties follow these strategies, negotiations are unlikely to succeed. This is known as bargaining failure. Moreover, this type of conduct is likely to fuel the negative emotions that are already present in a dispute and to increase the cognitive barriers to conflict resolution. Besides letting a neutral third party decide the issue, to which we turn in the next section, there is one basic technology for helping parties settle distributive issues in a fair way. Market prices, rules of thumb used in practice, social norms, or case law provide people with information about the way others dealt with similar problems (Fisher, Ury et al. 1991; Shell 2006). These “objective criteria” can help parties negotiating in a bilateral monopoly situation assess the fairness of outcomes, which is often difficult for them (Pillutla and Murnighan 2003; Husted and Folger 2004; Cialdini 2007). These objective criteria do not have to be binding legal norms. Information on how others actually settled distributive issues, or suggestions on how they might settle, are probably more effective than information on how they should settle (Barendrecht and Verdonschot 2008; Verdonschot 2009). Both types of information contribute to a shadow of the law, a neutral image of a just world, that makes it easier to settle differences (Mnookin and Kornhauser 1978; Cooter, Marks et al. 1982; Hacker 2008; Nisenbaum 2009; Ray 2009). Some authors have noted that objective criteria have a function in a dispute comparable to information about a market price in a standard economic transaction (Barendrecht and Verdonschot 2008). Knowing what the going rate for the good or service is on the market, helps both parties negotiate the price. Objective criteria give information about this going rate. This ‘pricing information’ is particularly helpful in the setting of disputes, where there is a bilateral monopoly, since the alternative of going to another buyer or seller for the disputed goods is not available (Yeazell 2008). Task Best Practices for Dispute Services/Transactions Possible Providers of Services 3. Share - Bargaining assistance (distributive negotiations) - Objective norms and criteria for most common issues in most common disputes - Make this information widely available in order to increase transparency - Advisers - Lawyers - Mediators (evaluative) - Legislators - Courts rendering precedents - Legal academics - Legal information providers (publishers) Table 5 Best Practices for Facilitating the Dispute System Task of Sharing Service Providers (adapted from Barendrecht 2009) 2. Objective Criteria for Distributive Issues as a Public Good and Experience Good There is likely to be a need for objective criteria and thus there should be a market for producing them. Unfortunately, objective criteria are again a type of information and we have seen that information may have characteristics that makes it difficult to sell. Producing meaningful information about the going rates of justice is costly. It requires extensive knowledge about the ways disputes of a certain type are settled or decided by neutrals. Outcomes of disputes tend to be individualized, taking many of the circumstances of the case into account. Discovering the patterns in decisions and translating them in useful rules of thumb is necessary. Once the rule is published, however, the marginal costs of letting another person use the information is close to zero, and it is very difficult to exclude people from using the information. Everyone is free to use and copy a norm for his private use. Thus, there is little commercial incentive to produce information about rules regarding suitable ways to deal with distributive issues (Posner and Rasmusen 1999; Parisi 2000). �� � � It is interesting to explore the parallel with information about prices on markets for consumer goods a little further. Price transparency is a condition for efficient markets, but it is not self evident that such information is produced, because it is costly to collect this information and display it. Stock markets, for instance, let buyers and sellers quote their prices, and thus contribute to the transparency of prices. Demonstrating that this information is valuable, stock markets try to protect pricing information through intellectual property rights and through contracts (Mulherin, Netter et al. 1991). Another reason why the ‘going rates’ of justice are not published, may be that a person who makes them transparent is likely to be criticized. He may be accused of being biased by interest groups from both sides. Repeat-players, or more generally those with more negotiating power, may also have an interest in keeping such going rates secret so that their opponents are unsure what a reasonable settlement is. Insurance companies, for example, tend not to publish the going rates for settlements in personal injury cases. This may induce some people to fight on, but the majority of plaintiffs are likely to accept a comparatively low settlement. 3. Consequences: Business Models for Selling Legal Information The scarcity of information about fair ways to settle distributive issues is a problem to which solutions have been found. The market for legal expertise developed in the same way as the one for communication and negotiation know how. Lawyers offer tailor made legal advice about the likely outcome of a dispute. They bundle this legal information with other services, such as helping parties to write a contract or to argue a case in court. People with knowledge about legal norms can also package the information in a book or a course, hoping the package will sell. Whether the market for legal information satisfies the need for objective criteria has not been researched to date. Some anecdotal evidence suggests that the market does not easily produce the type of information about the going rates of justice that disputants need. The market for legal information is a multi-billion market, but case law digests and handbooks are not accessible for lay people. Moreover, they tend not to give much guidance about the way people usually solve their most common disputes: divorce, termination of employment, conflicts between owners and users of land, water rights, or problems with suppliers of goods and services. Lawyers, judges, and repeat- players like insurance companies may know the going rates for settling such disputes, but they do not seem very eager to publish them. Some writers suggest that the legal profession has an interest in keeping the legal system complex and non-transparent, as this creates more demand for legal services (Hadfield 2000). There may be truth in this, but it is probably part of the more general truth that expertise is difficult to sell because information is a public good and an experience good. Lawyers, just like doctors, architects or IT giants have an interest to distribute their know how to one client at a time, and in a way that makes it difficult to resell the information. D. Delivering the Option of a Neutral Decision 1. Basic Technology The possibility to reach a final decision is an essential element of a dispute system. The basic technology for this is the option to address a neutral decision maker like a court. The need for a neutral decision may appear self-evident, but it is important to explore the different ways in which a plaintiff profits from this service (Lempert 1978). In Section A, we saw that the threat of a neutral intervention is an incentive for the defendant to meet and talk, particularly for those defendants who feel better off now, than they expect to be after a fair solution to the dispute. Once the communication and negotiation process takes off, the same incentives are needed to let the defendant make moves towards a fair and reasonable solution for the distributive issues. In a way, ���� � the neutral also supervises the negotiations, because both parties know that they can be brought to court to evaluate their points of view. Moreover, someone must make a decision if negotiations continue to fail, particularly if the parties do not reach agreement on the distributive issues ("bargaining failure" see Section C and Barendrecht 2008). “No deal” is a fully acceptable outcome if people are looking for partners to conclude arms length market transactions. But in a dispute, where there is a bilateral monopoly with very unattractive outside options, no deal usually equals injustice. The costs of access to neutral interventions such as courts (direct monetary costs, as well as time spent, costs of delay, and costs of stress and the like) are essential parameters of a dispute system. Table 6 lists some best practices for creating access to a neutral decision at low costs. High costs of access to courts are an often cited problem in dispute systems (Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor 2008). High litigation costs are not only problematic because they make the service of neutral intervention very expensive, they also dilute the other effects of access to a neutral decision maker (Barendrecht 2008). In order to avoid the negative effects of high litigation costs on the process and the outcome of settlement negotiations, the expected litigation costs should be small compared to the value at stake. An often mentioned criterion is that the sum of decision costs and error costs should be minimized (Tullock 1980; Shavell 2004; Cabrillo and Fitzpatrick 2008). Assuming that the probability of error is not very high, and the costs of error are not more than the value at stake, the litigation costs should be in the range of 10 to 15% of the value at stake, preferably less. Is this the type of neutral interventions that are available on the market for dispute resolution services? Task Best Practices for Dispute Services/Transactions Possible Providers of Services 4. Decide - Adjudication - Simple procedure (oral presentation, hearing, decision) - Limited fact-finding - Judicial/neutral case-management and information processing - Online formats for defining interests, distributive issues, possible solutions, decisions - Stimulate cooperative attitude - Procedural justice: voice, participation, trustworthiness, neutrality, interpersonal respect. - Discussion of possible objective criteria for outcome - Integration of decision making and settlement - Mild time pressure - Preliminary judgments in more difficult cases - More generally: minimize sum of decision costs and error costs - Persons with informal power - Courts - Arbitrators - Neutral fact-finders - State agencies Table 6 Best Practices for Facilitating the Dispute System Task of Deciding and Service Providers (adapted from Barendrecht 2009) 2. Buying a Neutral Intervention: A Troublesome Transaction There are many people who like to help others to solve their disputes, either as volunteers or for profit. Arbitration services are widely available. Experts who can solve distributive issues, such as valuation of property, determination of damages, or the amount of liability, can easily be found on the market. As we saw, the market for patronage provides a very natural recourse for a plaintiff who wants a defendant to make a move. Powerful people make a business of protecting others. Ideally, both parties contract with the same person who will then provide a neutral decision. But for this, the parties have to agree that this particular neutral is able to decide their dispute in a fair and just way. For the reasons discussed in Section A, this is difficult, and once the neutral is appointed, the same coordination problems subsist. During a dispute resolution procedure, the parties are unlikely to jointly agree on what exactly the neutral must do and on the costs of the services that they will buy from the neutral. Each decision on this influences the process, and the process influences the outcome, so the procedure becomes a strategic issue. The mindset of the disputants, who tend to distrust proposals from the other side, creates additional barriers. So the neutral does not receive ���� � guidance from his clients. His position is comparable to a builder of a home for a couple that disagrees about everything from the color of the tiles in the bathroom, to the number of stories the house should have, and even the budget for the project. The only thing on which they seem to agree, is that he should build a house. If we go back to the sources of transaction costs discussed in Section IIB, the setting described has many attributes that point into the direction of high transaction costs: 1. Once the parties have addressed a neutral, it is costly to switch to another adjudicator because that would mean that they would have to agree on opting out from the contract with the first neutral. Even if they would succeed in this agreement, the investments in informing the first neutral are partly wasted and they will have to inform the new neutral about their individual case (asset specificity). The parties are thus dependent on the neutral, who is unlikely to be fired. 2. The transaction between two parties and one neutral is typically a one time affair, so there is little discipline by the prospect of future interactions (low frequency). 3. Both parties expect the neutral to reign in the other party and to leave themselves room for manoeuvering, which makes the services of the neutral complex. Unexpected conduct of the other party causes much uncertainty and makes it very difficult to write a precise contract about what can be expected from the neutral (uncertainty and complexity). 4. Because both parties have different needs and expectations, it is difficult to measure and monitor performance of neutrals in dispute resolution processes, especially if there are no objective criteria against which the disputants can assess whether they obtained a fair solution. The difficulties of assessing the work of the neutral and the possibility of future interactions between one of the parties and the neutral create easy opportunities for corruption (difficult monitoring). 5. As we saw, low cost interventions by neutrals are very important as support for negotiations and to letting the parties come to the table in the first place. If there are no courts or other neutrals available, the market for other dispute resolution activities will deteriorate (connectedness with other transactions). 3. Consequences: Access to Neutrals is Unavailable or Unreliable For the plaintiff, concluding a transaction with a neutral for a procedure in which the defendant participates is thus extremely troublesome. Providers of dispute services have tried to find a solution for this by stimulating the parties to a relationship to choose a way to solve the dispute before they are in a situation of conflict. But this solution – an ex ante dispute resolution agreement – only works if the parties formalize their relationship in a contract (Shavell 1995; Eisenberg and Miller 2006; Sternlight 2007). That is unlikely to take place for many common relationships like marriage, informal employment, or informal tenure of land. For other sources of disputes – crimes by strangers, neighbour issues, or accidents resulting in personal injury – it is almost unthinkable that an agreement is reached before the conflict arises. So most plaintiffs have to rely on persons that have influence over the other party, but are not bound to any agreement with the plaintiff or the defendant about the way they will use this influence. They do not only have to think about ways the other party will be influenced, but also about strategies for keeping this person in check. The defendant faces a similar problem if the powerful person is intervening. Both parties will have to mobilize others to monitor the neutral and hope that he has sufficient interest in maintaining a reputation for neutral and helpful interventions in conflicts. This is an area in which the costs of market transactions apparently are so high, that governments have stepped in. They provide neutrals in the form of independent judges. This partly solves the problem of the plaintiff, but it remains to be seen whether this government agent has sufficient incentives to help the parties solve their disputes in a fair and low cost manner. Most commentators ���� � doubt whether the incentives on courts to provide adequate services to clients are sufficient (Messick 1999; Frynas 2001; López de Silanes 2002; Hammergren 2007; Cabrillo and Fitzpatrick 2008) . E. Making Arrangements Explicit and Enforcement 1. Basic Technology After the conflict has been resolved, the disputants need to find a new equilibrium. A property conflict, for instance, may be settled by allocating ownership to one of the parties, giving temporary rights of use to the other party, a payment, and/or a share in the proceeds if the property is sold with a profit within two years. These arrangements stabilize the relationship and make transparent what the parties can expect from each other in the future. Justice services can facilitate this stabilization process by offering ways to make arrangements explicit. Contracts, settlement agreements, and written judgments help to make explicit what parties can expect from each other in the future. Identity documents (birth certificates and other documents proving a person’s status) are useful tools for relationships between people who do not know each other in person. Property rights can be registered, so that they are transparent to everyone. These instruments are part of a broader technology of making the essentials of future relationships transparent. Relationships can be more fruitful if the parties know each others’ interests (needs, wishes and fears), exchange their expectations regarding the relationship, and have criteria for evaluating the relationship. They can also profit more from the relationship if their tasks and obligations are clear, they agree about allocation of possible gains and losses, and they have procedures to cope with differences. In this paper, the point of departure is a dispute, where two parties experience a conflict of interests that they cannot easily resolve. The outcome, then, is a set of tasks and understandings for the future. Making the essence of the relationship explicit can also happen at the moment the parties enter into the relationship, or at a later time during the transaction. By doing this, the parties may be able to prevent conflict, or can manage it more easily, because their ‘contract’ limits the possible points of contention. For stabilization to occur, the parties should also have sufficient reasons to live up to the outcomes that are agreed upon by the parties or imposed on them by the neutral. For the defendant in particular, compliance must be more attractive than non-compliance. The technology for enforcement is usually described in terms of monitoring performance and then by sanctions that are applied through reputation mechanisms (naming, shaming) or otherwise (fines, collective punishment like exclusion from future transactions). Nevertheless, the rewards from compliance in terms of future gains from relationships can be just as important. Table 7 suggests some ways to achieve compliance. Tasks Best Practices for Dispute Services/Transactions Possible Providers of Services 5. Stabilize - Standard negotiating, settlement, and decision documents (contracts/registrations) for most common disputes and issues; - Registrations, contracts, regulation (may be costly) - Informal compliance mechanisms (reputation, reciprocity, identification, authority) - Expected sanctions and rewards - Lawyers, mediators, notaries, other legal advisers - Community pressure - State agencies - Police - Bailiffs Table 7 Best Practices for Facilitating Dispute System Task of Stabilizing and Service Providers (adapted from Barendrecht 2009) 2. Transaction Costs of Services that Stabilize Relationships Creating stability can again be seen as a matter of transactions of the plaintiff and the defendant with people that help them to arrange it. Making the future relationship explicit can be done by a ���� � transaction with a registrar, lawyer, mediator, notary, or court. Again, it requires the cooperation of the two parties to hire this type of help, so this may be a first source of transaction costs. As lawyers involved in writing contracts know, the process of making relationships explicit can easily lead to renewed conflict. Disputes may flare up again during this stabilization phase, so it can be necessary to have a neutral available again. Getting access to a neutral a second time does not create new transaction costs problems, so we do not have to repeat the analysis of Section D. The second source of transaction costs should also be familiar at this point. Expert knowledge is required to make relationships transparent by registering property rights, writing contracts that settle a dispute, and formulating obligations for the future. Because of the public good character of this information, it may be that the market for assistance with writing judgments, (settlement) contracts and other ways to make expectations explicit does not reach the poor (see Sections B and C in relation to conflict management knowhow and objective criteria for settling distributive issues). The transactions necessary for creating enforcement are rather complicated. If the parties have difficulties monitoring how the other party lives up to the arrangement, a person can be hired to oversee enforcement. Sometimes the monitoring task can be performed by a group of people in the community, or by a dedicated organization such as a consumer organization. The transaction costs of organizing these groups can be quite substantial, because many people have to be convinced to participate. Taking collective action can be difficult because of free rider problems. In addition, it is usually not possible to buy all reasons for the defendant to live up to the agreement from one source. Such reasons can be provided by the plaintiff himself, who can withhold benefits from the settlement contract to the defendant, by members from the community, who can make the defendant suffer from a bad reputation, or by third parties who can apply sanctions. The literature on creating self-enforcing contracts and setting up private enforcement mechanisms is vast and gives a good impression of the transaction costs involved (MacLeod 2007; Chakravarty, MacLeod et al. 2008). Sanctions such as a fine or even exclusion from the community are costly to apply for those who have to administer it. Thus, a third party hired to perform the sanctioning task may try to renege on his obligation to apply the sanction. Trade organizations, for instance, will think twice before excluding one of their members, because of the additional conflict this may cause. A plaintiff will rely on the sanctioning system infrequently, so there are no repeated interactions between him and the ones imposing sanctions. Damage to reputation will only work if a number of people are interested hearing about the non-compliance and willing to withhold items from the defendant that are more important to him than the gains from non-compliance. Even consumer organizations are not always able to organize this. Complexity and connected transactions are thus also sources of transaction costs. 3. Consequences: Stabilization Difficult to Obtain for People with Limited Resources Justice markets have to cope with these transaction costs. Making future relationships explicit through contracts or other documentation can be standardized. But it is difficult to find a business model for these transactions, because they involve transfer of information. So legal service providers revert to the usual approaches to selling expertise (individualization and packaging) and people with limited resources have little access to these services, Providers of enforcement have to look for economies of scale in order to diminish transaction costs. They are likely to use a variety of strategies: influencing the reputation of the defendant, positive encouragement through the promise of future gains, and threats of imposing sanctions on the defendant. These services will not be easily accessible to the poor in their relations to the powerful and resource rich, because poor people will have more difficulties to find others who are both willing to support them and can exert influence over the defendant. ���� � F. Complementarities A dispute system is more than the sum of its parts. The five tasks a dispute system has to perform are linked. If one of the tasks is performed more efficiently, it often becomes easier to perform other tasks (Bendersky 2003). In this section, these linkages are analyzed as causes of extra transaction costs. 1. Connectedness between Dispute Services Whether it is worthwhile to meet in order to resolve a dispute cooperatively, depends on the expectations of both parties concerning the next four steps in a dispute resolution process. For a plaintiff, it is much more attractive to start a process if he knows that he will be able to use low cost/high quality services that help him to communicate and negotiate, and to get a fair share in the distributive issues. If the negotiations fail, the plaintiff will also need a third party to decide. Finally, both a negotiated outcome and a decision by this third party should be enforceable. Transaction cost economics identifies connectedness between different types of transactions as an important source of transaction costs (see Section IIB). Minimizing these costs is often the goal of governance structures such as alliances, networks of suppliers, and vertical integration in the supply chain (Dyer and Singh 1998). Services that help people to negotiate disputes (mediation, negotiation services by lawyers or others, education in dispute resolution skills) also have complementarities with other elements of the dispute system. Negotiated outcomes are more likely to be complied with than imposed outcomes (research about mediated settlements reports compliance rates as high as 90%), because the parties “own” the outcome. Thus better communication and negotiation services make compliance services easier to deliver. Publication of objective criteria for distributive issues is another service with complementarities. Objective criteria not only facilitate bargaining and reduce the probability of bargaining failure, but also enable clients to monitor whether their lawyers obtained good results for them in negotiations and whether neutrals make fair decisions. Buying corrupt judges, as well as less obvious ways to influence the outcome, will become more difficult and less effective. Such norms are also likely to make proceedings before a neutral adjudicator less complicated, because both the parties and the neutral can focus on the application of the criteria, which decreases litigation costs (Kaplow 1992). If social norms (objective criteria) about distributive issues are more transparent, non-compliance of outcomes based on these criteria is also more easily detectable. Reputation mechanisms and other informal sanctions are then easier to apply. Because of these complementarities, economists will predict that there less investment in the production of objective criteria than would be the case under perfect competition, the reason being that producers of objective criteria cannot profit from the gains that they cause on these adjacent markets. There are also strong links between the negotiation process and adjudication (Bendersky 2003). Without the option of a low cost neutral intervention, negotiations will take longer and be more costly, with a higher risk of impasse. Judges are dependent on the parties for defining the issues and for giving them information and can go on where the parties got stuck in the negotiations. Information exchanged in the negotiation process is similar to what is needed in litigation, which can lead to important cost savings. If the quality of the litigation process is high, delivering procedural justice to clients, enforcement becomes easier (Tyler 2007; Hollander-Blumoff and Tyler 2008). 2. Integrated Services These complementarities are well noted by the players on the market for justice. Commercial legal services providers often offer their clients more than one dispute resolution service. Integration of services into one firm is one possible answer to a problem of complementarities, because it ensures ���� � that both the connected services are delivered, and that clients obtain access to the added value of the combination. Most lawyers offer packages of services. They assist their clients in negotiations, give them legal information, and help them with accessing the neutral. When it comes to a final outcome in litigation, a lawyer is also likely to help his client with enforcing the outcome. Mediators also found out that integrated services are more profitable. Besides facilitating the negotiations between the clients with conflict management skills, many mediators also give their clients an evaluation of their legal positions (Wall, Stark et al. 2001). This evaluative mediation has effects very similar to a decision in summary proceedings by a common law court, or a decision in first instance in a civil law procedure. If one of the parties does not agree with the outcome imposed by this neutral, he can appeal at the next level of the court system. Even judges have found it profitable to go beyond adjudication. Both arbiters and courts now routinely offer their clients some help with negotiating a settlement, and have also diversified the way of adjudication. US courts deliver more settlements than decisions, and more summary judgements than verdicts after a trial (Hadfield 2004). By referring parties to court-annexed mediation, they even offer higher value services in relation to the settlement task. In some countries, adjudicators are also involved in enforcement of judgments (Kennett 2000; Henderson, Shah et al. 2004). In addition, courts have always been providers of objective criteria through their case law, albeit in a limited way. For clients, integration is not always beneficial. If lawyers give advice regarding settlement processes and ways to distribute value, this may be influenced by their personal interest to sell additional services as a litigator. There are doubts whether it is desirable that mediators, who facilitate integrative negotiations, should also advise about suitable solutions on distributive issues (evaluative mediation). The integration has not yet been complete, however. The market does not provide integrated dispute resolution services from letting parties meet, facilitating their negotiations, providing objective criteria, to deciding distributive issues and organizing compliance for them. Whether such integrated services are possible at all, remains to be seen (see Barendrecht 2009 for a description of a possible model). V. Conclusions So, what have we learned about the capabilities of markets to deliver justice? This paper analyzed how plaintiffs can be served on five markets that satisfy their demand for justice. A plaintiff may need (1) help with creating incentives for the defendant to meet and solve a conflict cooperatively, (2) assistance with integrative negotiations, (3) objective criteria for distributive issues, (4) low cost access to a neutral decision, and (5) help with stabilization of the relationship by making expectations explicit and by providing incentives on the defendant to live up to outcomes. A preliminary analysis of these five markets shows that each has its own sources of transaction costs. These transaction costs explain many characteristics of the market for justice. Table 8 summarizes the results. One conclusion from the analysis is that markets contribute more to solving disputes than we usually assume. Most disputes are managed without government intervention. The market can provide incentives on defendants to cooperate, negotiation assistance and norms that help to settle distributive issues. It can also provide neutrals, help people to make relationships explicit, and do much to organize enforcement. There is no single element of a dispute system that cannot be provided by the market. ���� � Tasks Basic technology Sources of Transaction Costs Market reactions 1. Meet Make costs and benefits of participation for defendant higher than costs and benefits of fighting, or avoiding 1. Difficulties of concluding ex post dispute resolution agreements: - Psychological barriers - Strategic barriers 2. Cooperation between many people needed to organize sufficient incentives on powerful defendants to cooperate 1. Little demand for mediation, arbitration, and other tailor made neutral dispute services 2. Unilateral advice where neutral services would be more efficient 3. Demand for patronage (help from people who can influence the defendant) 4. Demand for checks and balances 2.Talk Support integrative negotiation (interest based) Information about negotiation and conflict management is public good 1. Insufficient supply 2. Business models for delivering expertise: - individualized advice - coaching client through process - taking over process from client - packaging information 3. Problems with access for clients with limited resources 3. Share Supply information about fair shares (sharing rules, objective criteria) 1. Information about fair solutions is public good 2. Providers of fairness information face pressure/criticism from all sides 1. Insufficient supply 2. Business models for delivering expertise (see above) 3. Problems with access for clients with limited resources 4. Decide Make option of a neutral decision available (at low cost) 1. Difficulties of concluding ex post dispute resolution agreements: - Psychological barriers - Strategic barriers 2. Insufficient incentives on neutral to provide efficient processes and fair solutions because of: - dependence on neutral - low frequency of transactions - uncertainty and complexity - monitoring difficulties. 1. Access to neutrals on markets is unavailable or unreliable 2. States provide neutrals (effectiveness doubtful) 5. Stabilize Supply tools to make arrangements explicit; Make costs and benefits of compliance higher than those of non-compliance Information about contracting and making relationships transparent is public good Cooperation between many people needed to organize sufficient incentives on powerful defendants to cooperate 1. Insufficient supply 2. Business models for delivering expertise 3. Lack of enforcement, in particular against powerful defendants Supply Chain Approach Strengthen links between tasks Complementarities/connectedness between the five types of services Integrated business models for providing unilateral legal services, mediation and adjudication Table 8: Sources of Transaction Costs on Markets for Justice and Ways Markets Cope with Them It would be wrong, however, to conclude that markets can be left on their own to dispense justice. On the contrary, we encountered three major reasons why demand and supply for justice services do not meet in such a way that justice is universally accessible. First, buying justice services is difficult because two opponents are unlikely to agree on the kind of service they need. Disputants may experience psychological barriers that make it difficult to enter a cooperative procedure, and often also have strategic reasons for not agreeing on a procedure. These coordination problems persist during the dispute resolution process. When courts or other neutrals decide disputes, they thus experience insufficient incentives from their clients to supply high quality and low cost procedures. A second source of high transaction costs relates to dispute services that consist of providing expertise. Such information tends to be difficult to sell for a profit. It has a public good character, is an experience good, and the costs of production can be rather high compared. As a consequence, conflict management skills (integrative negotiation know how), objective criteria for settling ���� � distributive issues, and relationship formats (contracts) are delivered through business models that do not always reach the persons that need them most: those with limited resources. Third, justice transactions tend to have a higher value if other justice transactions are also available. Negotiation assistance and neutral decision making by courts, for instance, work better if objective criteria for settling distributive issues are available. The incentives for defendants to solve conflicts cooperatively and to live up to outcomes typically come from the joint effects of monitoring, the value of reputation, the threat of informal sanctions, internal motivation, and formal enforcement. Many people have to cooperate to make this happen. These complementarities, network-effects, or connected transactions require an integrated approach. There is much room for improvement of this analysis. Other break-downs in constituent parts may reflect the realities on justice markets in a better way. Our analysis departed from a conflict as the trigger to address justice services, and assumed that actions taken by plaintiffs seeking help in conflicts gradually create a legal system in a bottom-up manner. We only touched briefly how group interests and group processes are used to obtain access to justice. The demand for protection of interests and rights that may exist before a conflict materializes deserves further study as well. Finally, we concentrated on access to justice for plaintiffs, who want to achieve a change in the status quo, and not on the position of defendants. Taking other points of departure may disclose other types of essential services, other sources of transaction costs, and other ways to minimize them. But we were able to explain many characteristics of the market for justice. Legal services tend to be individualized, because this is the business model that can cope with the public good character of information. There is little commoditization. Thus, information about conflict management and about fair outcomes is difficult to access for defendants with limited resources. Justice also tends to be a luxury good because many people need to cooperate in order to reign in powerful defendants. Unilateral advice is much more common than jointly addressing a mediator or adjudicator, although that is generally an efficient way to solve a dispute. In this paper, we did not discuss the policy implications. These also depends on the likely transaction costs of government interventions. For the time being, our analysis suggests that governments should focus on ways to diminish the three major sources of transaction costs we discussed. They should help parties agree on an efficient procedure and coordinate their transactions with third parties; ensure that the going rates of justice and conflict management know how are available that markets fail to provide; and facilitate coordination between the many transactions that make justice happen in the real world. For instance in the life of a woman in Ndirande, who needs a place where she can safely discuss with the family of her deceased husband what should happen to the house and their other assets. She needs innovative services that bring essential information to her: guidance how to conduct these discussions and criteria for settling the issues in a fair manner. These services would not be free, but hopefullly they would be affordable for her. She needs some assistance to form a network of relationships that ensures cooperation from the family of her man. She needs tools to ensure the shadow of a neutral decision by someone she can trust. Justice will emerge spontaneously because people demand it. But some thoughtful policies that decrease the costs of shopping for justice may help. �� � � Literature Akerlof, G. A. (1970). "The market for" lemons": quality uncertainty and the market mechanism." The quarterly journal of economics: 488-500. Allred, K. G. (2005). Relationship Dynamics in Disputes: Replacing Contention with Cooperation. Handbook of Dispute Resolution. M. L. Moffitt and R. C. Bordone. New York, Jossey-Bass: 83-98. Anderson, M. R. (2003). Access to justice and legal process: making legal institutions responsive to poor people in LDCs, Institute of Development Studies at the University of Sussex. Arrow, K. J. (1995). Barriers to Conflict Resolution, WW Norton & Company. Baarsma, B., F. A. Felsö, et al. (2008). Regulation of the legal profession and access to law, Report commissioned by the International Association of Legal Expenses Insurance (RIAD), SEO Economic Research. Barendrecht, M. (2008). In Search of Microjustice: Five Basic Elements of a Dispute System. SSRN. Barendrecht, M. (2009). "Best Practices for an Affordable and Sustainable Dispute System: A Toolbox for Microjustice." SSRN. Barendrecht, M. and B. R. De Vries (2006). "Fitting the Forum to the Fuss with Sticky Defaults: Failure on the Market for Dispute Resolution Services? ." Cardozo Journal of Conflict Resolution 7(1). Barendrecht, M., P. Kamminga, et al. (2008). Priorities for the Justice System: Responding to the Most Urgent Legal Problems of Individuals, SSRN. Barendrecht, M. and P. Van Nispen (2008). Microjustice, SSRN. Barendrecht, M. and J. H. Verdonschot (2008). Objective Criteria: Facilitating Dispute Resolution by Information About Going Rates of Justice, SSRN. Bendersky, C. (2003). "Organizational dispute resolution systems: A complementarities model." The Academy of Management Review: 643-656. Bingham, L. B. (2008). "Designing Justice: Legal Institutions and Other Systems for Managing Conflict." Ohio St. J. on Disp. Resolution. Bone, R. G. (2008). "Making Effective Rules: The Need for Procedure Theory." Oklahoma Law Review 61. Bordone, R. C. (2008). Dispute System Design: An Introduction. Botero, J. C., R. La Porta, et al. (2003). The World Bank Research Observer 18(1): 61-88. Braun, P., J. Brzostowski, et al. (2006). "e-Negotiation systems and software agents: methods, models, and applications." Intelligent Decision-Making Support Systems: Foundation, Applications, and Challenges, Springer Verlag. Brett, J. M., M. Olekalns, et al. (2007). "Sticks and Stones: Language, Face, and Online Dispute Resolution." The Academy of Management Journal (AMJ) 50(1): 85-99. Buck, A., P. Pleasence, et al. (2008). "Do Citizens Know How to Deal with Legal Issues? Some Empirical Insights." Journal of Social Policy 37(04): 661-681. Buscaglia, E. and P. B. Stephan (2005). "An empirical assessment of the impact of formal versus informal dispute resolution on poverty: A governance-based approach." International Review of Law and Economics 25(1): 89-106. Cabrillo, F. and S. Fitzpatrick (2008). The Economics of Courts and Litigation. Cheltenham, UK, Edward Elgar. Cappeletti, M. and B. Garth (1978). "Access to Justice: The Newest Wave in the Worldwide Movement to Make Rights Effective." Buffalo Law Review 27(181). Carothers, T., Ed. (2006). Promoting the Rule of Law Abroad: In Search of Knowledge. Washington D.C., Carnegie Endowment for International Peace. Carraro, C., C. Marchiori, et al. (2006). "Advances in Negotiation Theory: Bargaining, Coalitions and Fairness." World. Chakravarty, S., W. B. MacLeod, et al. (2008). "Contracting in the Shadow of the Law." NBER Working Paper. Cialdini, R. B. (2007). "Descriptive Social Norms As Underappreciated Sources Of Social Control." Psychometrika Vol. 72(No. 2): 6. Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor (2008). Making the Law Work for Everyone. I. Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor (2008). Making the Law Work for Everyone. II Working Group Reports. Cooter, R., S. Marks, et al. (1982). "Bargaining in the Shadow of the Law: A Testable Model of Strategic Behavior " The Journal of Legal Studies 11(2): 225-251 �� � � Costantino, C. A. and C. Sickles Merchant (1996). Designing conflict management systems. San Francisco, Jossey-Bass. Currie, J. and W. B. MacLeod (2008). "First Do No Harm? Tort Reform and Birth Outcomes*." Quarterly Journal of Economics 123(2): 795-830. Daughety, A. F. and J. F. Reinganum (2008). Settlement. Discussion Paper prepared for inclusion in the Encyclopedia of Law and Economics (2nd Ed.), Vol. 10: Procedural Law and Economics, Ed. by Chris William Sanchirico to be published by Edward Elgar. David, R. J. and S. K. Han (2004). "A systematic assessment of the empirical support for transaction cost economics." Strategic Management Journal 25(1). Dawson, R. (2005). Developing knowledge-based client relationships: leadership in professional services, Butterworth-Heinemann. De Soto, H. (2000). The Mystery of Captal; Why Capitalism Triumphs in the West and Fails Everywhere Else. New York. Deutsch, M., P. T. Coleman, et al. (2006). The Handbook of Conflict Resolution: Theory and Practice. San Francisco. Dixit, A. (2009). "Governance Institutions and Economic Activity." American Economic Review 99(1): 5-24. Dixit, A. K. (2004). Lawlessness and Economics: Alternative Modes of Governance, Princeton University Press. Djankov, S., R. La Porta, et al. (2003). "Courts." Quarterly Journal of Economics(May). Dyer, J. H. and H. Singh (1998). "The relational view: Cooperative strategy and sources of interorganizational competitive advantage." Academy of management review: 660-679. Eisenberg, T. and G. P. Miller (2006). The Flight from Arbitration: An Empirical Study of Ex Ante Arbitration Clauses in Publicly-Held Companies' Contracts, SSRN. Fisher, R., W. Ury, et al. (1991). Getting to yes: negotiating agreement without giving in. New York, N.Y., Penguin Books. French, J. R. P. and B. Raven (2001). The bases of social power. The Negotiation Sourcebook. I. G. Asherman and S. V. Asherman. Amherst, Mass., HRD Press: 61-82. Frynas, J. G. (2001). "Problems of access to courts in Nigeria: Results of a survey of legal practitioners." Social & Legal Studies 10(3): 397-419. Gennaioli, N. and A. Shleifer (2007). "The evolution of common law." Journal of Political Economy 115(1): 43-68. Golub, S. (2003). Beyond Rule of Law Orthodoxy: The Legal Empowerment Alternative, Carnegie Endowment for International Peace. Gramatikov, M. (2008). A Framework for Measuring the Costs of Paths to Justice, SSRN. Gramatikov, M. (2008). Multiple Justiciable Events in Bulgaria. Reaching Further: New Approaches to the Delivery of Legal Services. L. S. R. Centre. London: 22. Greif, A. (2006). Institutions and the path to the modern economy: Lessons from medieval trade, Cambridge University Press. Hacker, D. (2008). "A legal field in action: the case of divorce arrangements in Israel." International Journal of Law in Context 4(01): 1-33. Hadfield, G. (2008). "Legal Barriers to Innovation." Regulation 31(3): 14-21. Hadfield, G. and E. Talley (2006). "On Public versus Private Provision of Corporate Law." JOURNAL OF LAW ECONOMICS AND ORGANIZATION 22(2): 414. Hadfield, G. K. (2000). "The Price of Law: How the Market for Lawyers Distorts the Justice System." Michigan Law Review 98(4): 953-1006. Hadfield, G. K. (2004). "Delivering Legality on the Internet: Developing Principles for the Private Provision of Commercial Law." Am Law Econ Rev 6(1): 154-184. Hadfield, G. K. (2004). "Where Have All the Trials Gone? Settlements, Nontrial Adjudications, and Statistical Artifacts in the Changing Disposition of Federal Civil Cases." Journal of Empirical Legal Studies 1(3): 705-734. Hammergren, L. A. (2007). Envisioning Reform: Improving Judicial Performance in Latin America, Pennsylvania State University Press. Henderson, K., A. Shah, et al. (2004). "Regional Best Practices: Enforcement of Judgments: Lessons from Latin America." IFES, Rule of Law Paper Series, WashingtonDC. Hensler, D. R. (2002). "Suppose It's Not True: Challenging Mediation Ideology." Journal of Dispute Resolution. ���� � Hollander-Blumoff, R. and T. R. Tyler (2008). "Procedural Justice in Negotiation: Procedural Fairness, Outcome Acceptance, and Integrative Potential." Law & Social Inquiry 33(2): 473-500. Huang, K.-C. (2007). Does Dicovery Promote Settlement? - An Empirical Answer. 2007 Conference on Empirical Legal Studies. Husted, B. W. and R. Folger (2004). "Fairness and Transaction Costs: The Contribution of Organizational Justice Theory to an Integrative Model of Economic Organization." ORGANIZATION SCIENCE 15(6): 719-729. Jensen, E. G. (2002). The Rule of Law and Judicial Reform: The Political Economy of Diverse Institutional Patterns and Reformers’ Responses. Beyond Common Knowledge: Empirical Approaches to the Rule of Law. . E. G. Jensen and T. C. Heller, Stanford University Press. Kaplow, L. (1992). "Rules versus standards: an economic analysis." Duke Law Journal: 557-629. Katsh, E. E., M. E. Katsh, et al. (2001). Online Dispute Resolution: Resolving Conflicts in Cyberspace. New York, John Wiley & Sons, Inc. . Kennett, W. A. (2000). Enforcement of judgments in Europe, Oxford University Press. Kim, J. and J. T. Mahoney (2005). "Property rights theory, transaction costs theory, and agency theory: an organizational economics approach to strategic management." Managerial and Decision Economics 26(4): 223-42. Klement, A. and Z. Neeman (2009). Civil Justice Reform: A Mechanism Design Framework, SSRN. Korobkin, R. B. and J. W. Doherty (2007). Who Wins in Settlement Negotiations?, SSRN. Lande, J. (2005). "The Promise and Perils of Collaborative Law." Dispute Resolution Magazine 12. Lande, J. (2008). "Developing Better Lawyers and Lawyering Practices: Introduction to the Symposium on Innovative Models of Lawyering." Journal of Dispute Resolution(1). Lempert, R. (1978). "More tales of two courts: Exploring changes in the dispute settlement function of trial courts." Law & Society Review 13: 91. Lewicki, R. J., D. M. Saunders, et al. (2006). Negotiation Boston, McGraw Hill/Irwin. Libecap, G. D. (1989). Contracting for Property Rights, Cambridge University Press. López de Silanes, F. (2002). "The politics of legal reform." Economía: 91-136. Macher, J. T. and B. D. Richman (2008). "Transaction cost economics: An assessment of empirical research in the social sciences." Business and Politics 10(1): 1-63. MacLeod, W. B. (2007). "Reputations, Relationships, and Contract Enforcement." Journal of Economic Literature 45(3): 595-628. Messick, R. (1999). Reducing Court Delays: Five lessons from the United States. PREM notes, The World Bank. Milgrom, P. R. and J. Roberts (1992). Economics, organization and management, Prentice-Hall Englewood Cliffs, NJ. Mnookin, R. H. and L. Kornhauser (1978). "Bargaining in the Shadow of the Law: The Case of Divorce." Yale Law Journal 88: 950. Mnookin, R. H., S. R. Peppet, et al. (2000). Beyond Winning, Negotiating Deals To Create Value In Deals And Disputes. Cambridge Mass., The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. Mnookin, R. H., L. Susskind, et al. (1999). Negotiating on Behalf of Others, Sage Publications. Moffitt, M. L., R. C. Bordone, et al. (2005). The Handbook of Dispute Resolution, Jossey-Bass. Moore, C., W. (2003). The mediation process–Practical strategies for resolving conflict, . San Francisco, Jossey-Bass. Mulherin, J. H., J. M. Netter, et al. (1991). "Prices Are Property: The Organization of Financial Exchanges from a Transaction Cost Perspective." Journal of Law and Economics: 591-644. Muthoo, A. (1999). Bargaining Theory with Applications. Cambridge U.K., Cambridge University Press. Muthoo, A. (2000). "A Non-Technical Introduction to Bargaining Theory." World Economics 1(2): 145-166. Nisenbaum, S. (2009). Negotiation and the Shadow of Law. Handbook on Building Cultures of Peace. J. De Rivera: 245-257. Oetzel, J. G. and S. Ting-Toomey (2006). The SAGE handbook of conflict communication. Thousand Oaks, SAGE. Parisi, F. (2000). 9500 Spontaneous Emergence of Law: Customary Law. Encyclopedia of Law and Economics. B. Bouckaert and G. De Geest. Cheltenham, Edward Elgar. V The Economics of Crime and Litigation. Parker, C. (1999). Just lawyers, Oxford University Press. Pillutla, M. M. and J. K. Murnighan (2003). "Fairness in Bargaining." Social Justice Research,: 22. ���� � Pinkley, R. L., M. A. Neale, et al. (1994). "The impact of alternatives to settlement in dyadic negotiation." Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 57: 97-116. Ponzetto, G. A. M. and P. A. Fernandez (2008). "Case law versus statute law: an evolutionary comparison." The Journal of Legal Studies 37(2): 379-430. Posner, R. A. (1993). "What Do Judges and Justices Maximize? (The Same Thing Everybody Else Does)." Supreme Court Economic Review: 1-41. Posner, R. A. and E. B. Rasmusen (1999). "Creating and Enforcing Norms, with Special Reference to Sanctions." International Review of Law and Economics 19: 14. Raban, D. R. (2007). "User-centered evaluation of information: a research challenge." Internet Research 17(3): 306-322. Rao, P. K. (2003). The Economics of Transaction Costs; Theory, Methods, and Applications. New York, Palgrave MacMillan. Rapaczynski, A. (1996). "The Roles of the State and the Market in Establishing Property Rights." The Journal of Economic Perspectives: 87-103. Ray, B. (2009). Extending the Shadow of the Law: Using Hybrid Mechanisms to Develop Constitutional Norms in Socioeconomic Rights Cases: 2. Relis, T. (2002). "Civil Litigation from Litigants' Perspectives: What We Know and What We Don't Know About the Litigation Experience of Individual Litigants." Studies in Law, Politics and Society 25: 151-212. Rhode, D. L. (2004). Access to Justice. New York, Oxford University Press. Robson, A. and S. Skaperdas (2008). "Costly enforcement of property rights and the Coase theorem." Economic Theory 36(1): 109-128. Ross, L. (1995). Reactive Devaluation in Negotiation and Conflict Resolution. New York, W.W. Norton. . Schneider, M. R. (2005). "Judicial Career Incentives and Court Performance: An Empirical Study of the German Labour Courts of Appeal." European Journal of Law and Economics 20(2): 127-144. Shapiro, C. and H. R. Varian (1998). "Versioning: The smart way to sell information." Harvard Business Review: 107. Shariff, K. Z. (2003). "Designing Institutions to Manage Conflict: Principles for the Problem Solving Organization." Harvard Negotiation Law Review. Shavell, S. (1995). "Alternative dispute resolution: An economic analysis." The Journal of Legal Studies: 1- 28. Shavell, S. (2004). Foundations of Economic Analysis of Law Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press. Shell, R. (2006). Bargaining for Advantage:Negotiation Strategies for Rational People. London, Penguin Books. Stephen, F. and J. Love (1999). Regulation of law firms. Encyclopedia of Law and Economics. G. De Geest and B. Bouckaert. London, Edgar Elgar: 987-1017. Stephen, F. H. (2006). An Economic Perspective on the Regulation of Legal Service Markets. Sternlight, J. R. (2007). "In Defense of Mandatory Arbitration (If Imposed on the Company)." Nevada Law Journal 8. Stiglitz, J. (2000). Handbook of Economics of the Public Sector. Stiglitz, J. E. (1999). "Knowledge as a global public good." Global public goods 1(9): 308-326. Stipanowich, T. J. (2004). "ADR and the “Vanishing Trial”: the growth and impact of “Alternative Dispute Resolution”." Journal of Empirical Legal Studies 1(3): 843-912. Susskind, R. (2008). The End of Lawyers? Rethinking the Nature of Legal Services. Oxford, Oxford University Press. Tullock, G. (1980). Trials on Trial: The Pure Theory of Legal Procedure. New York, Columbia University Press. Tyler, T. R. (1997). Citizen Discontent with Legal Procedures: A Social Science Perspective on Civil Procedure Reform. Civil Procedure Reform in Comparative Context, Florence, Italy, New York University. Tyler, T. R. (2007). Psychology and the Design of Legal Institutions. Nijmegen, Wolf Legal Publishers. Ury, W. (1991). Getting past no: negotiating with difficult people. New York, Bantam Books. Ury, W. L., J. M. Brett, et al. (1988). Getting disputes resolved: Designing systems to cut the costs of conflict. San Francisco, Jossey Bass. ���� � Van Kleef, G. A., C. K. W. De Dreu, et al. (2006). "Supplication and Appeasement in Conflict and Negotiation: The Interpersonal Effects of Disappointment, Worry, Guilt, and Regret." Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 91: 124-142. Van Velthoven, B. J. and M. Ter Voert (2004). Geschilbeslechtingsdelta 2003. Den Haag, WODC. Varian, H. R. (1998). Markets for information goods. Velikonja, U. (2009). "Making Peace and Making Money: Economic Analysis of the Market for Mediators in Private Practice." Albany Law Review 72. Verdonschot, J. H. (2009). Delivering Objective Criteria: Sources of Law and the Relative Value of Neutral Information for Dispute Resolution, SSRN. Vossen, M. and M. Knapen (2009). Township Blues: Legal needs of individuals in Ndirande, Blantyre. Tilburg, Wereld Podium/Panga Press. Wall, J. A., Jr., J. B. Stark, et al. (2001). "Mediation: A Current Review and Theory Development." Journal Of Conflict Resolution 45(3): 370-391. Walton, R. and R. McKersie (1965). A Behavioral Theory of Labor Negotiations. Beverly Hills, Sage Publications. Williamson, O. E. (1981). "The Economics of Organization: The Transaction Cost Approach." American Journal of Sociology 87(3): 548. Williamson, O. E. (1999). "Public and private bureaucracies: a transaction cost economics perspectives." J Law Econ Organ 15(1): 306-342. Wissler, R. L. (2004). "The effectiveness of court-connected dispute resolution in civil cases." Conflict Resolution Quarterly 22(1-2): 55-88. Wojkowska, E. (2006). Doing Justice: How informal justice systems can contribute. United Nations Development Programme, Oslo Governance Centre, The Democratic Governance Fellowship Programme. Yeazell, S. (2008). Transparency for Civil Settlements: NASDAQ for Lawsuits?, SSRN. Zuckerman, A. A. S., S. Chiarloni, et al. (1999). Civil justice in crisis: comparative perspectives of civil procedure, Oxford University Press. work_bsii5lg75felphsnik3eirzuma ---- 1 Sovereign Wealth Funds and Global Justice Chris Armstrong, University of Southampton Forthcoming in Ethics and International Affairs Abstract: Dozens of countries have established Sovereign Wealth Funds (SWFs) in the last decade or so, in the majority of cases employing those Funds to manage the large revenues gained from selling resources such as oil and gas on a tide of rapidly rising commodity prices. These Funds have raised a series of ethical questions, including just how the money contained in such Funds should eventually be spent. This paper engages with that question, and specifically seeks to connect debates on SWFs with debates on global justice. Just how good are national claims to the great wealth contained in SWFs in the first place? Using the example of Norway’s very large SWF – derived from selling North-Sea petroleum – I show that national claims are at least sometimes very weak, with the implication that the wealth in many such Funds is ripe for redistribution in the interests of global justice. I conclude by offering some guidance for how the money contained in such Funds could best be spent, with the goal of advancing global justice. Keywords: Sovereign Wealth Funds – Natural Resources – Justice – Global Justice - Redistribution Introduction Dozens of countries have established Sovereign Wealth Funds in the last decade or so, in the majority of cases employing those Funds to manage the large revenues gained from selling resources such as oil and gas on a tide of rapidly rising commodity prices. Rather than using those revenues for day-to-day government expenditure, Sovereign Wealth Funds ring-fence them for longer-term investments or to smooth expenditure over time in the light of impending pension 2 crises. In building diverse portfolios on international stock and real estate markets, states also reduce their vulnerability to fluctuating exchange rates, volatile commodity prices, or the likely exhaustion of natural resource supplies in the decades to come. The existence and activities of such Funds (hereafter SWFs) has, though, prompted a number of ethical discussions: how should SWFs be organised, in order to ensure that their governance is at least minimally legitimate? 1 Should they avoid investing in ecologically-damaging or otherwise dubious industries overseas? When foreign SWFs provide much-needed sources of investment for countries such as the US, should this raise concerns about national security and political independence? 2 Though they have received far less attention to date, there are equally important questions about what these Funds are for – about how the money in SWFs should eventually be distributed, and to whom. Some Funds, as in the well-known Alaskan example, have been used to generate a (modest) Basic Income for all citizens. A few others are intended to ease shortfalls in pension entitlements. These cases, though, are rather exceptional. 3 Most SWFs, rather than ameliorating inequalities or subsidising the consumption of the poor, for example, are intended to finance unspecified future infrastructure projects, or, in some high-profile cases, to finance prestige projects for ruling families. 4 Even insofar as ethical debates have begun to touch on how the money in the Funds should be distributed, they have tended to ask how these assets should be distributed internally, to citizens of the countries which have established those Funds. Sovereign Wealth Funds are the creation of sovereigns, after all, and we might think that the first virtue of a sovereign is to treat the citizens he or she is responsible for equally. 5 What, though, of the claims of global justice? 6 The money in the bulk of these SWFs, as already indicated, is derived from selling natural resources (usually of the petrochemical variety). But the distribution of natural resources has frequently been thought to raise issues of global justice. Isn’t the distribution of natural resource wealth across the globe simply ‘arbitrary,’ from a moral point of view? Is it just that some communities should be so hugely advantaged simply because they have plentiful supplies of valuable resources? Would the proceeds of these Funds not be better used to attack global poverty, or to reduce global inequalities? 7 The many discussions of SWFs within the field of international political economy have not yet addressed their potential to help ameliorate global injustice. Theorists of global justice, for their part, have not yet turned their attention to the significance of SWFs as vehicles of natural resource wealth – wealth which might, from the point of view of justice, be vulnerable to calls for redistribution. This paper seeks to remedy that mutual neglect. In section 1 I provide a brief overview of one of the world’s very largest SWFs, established by the Norwegian government. There 3 are two reasons for focusing on the Norwegian case. First, Norway is one of the wealthiest countries in the world, and this fact accentuates the tension between pursuing goals of national and global justice. For a poorer country to maintain a SWF – and to use its proceeds to ease domestic poverty - might be less objectionable from the point of view of global justice. But Norway is a very rich country by anyone’s standards and the projects of domestic justice which its Fund is charged to advance are less obviously compatible with the demands of global justice. Second, Norway’s SWF is frequently held up as the world’s leading example of good practice in terms of both its transparency 8 and its ethical investment strategy. 9 It has even been criticised for placing too much emphasis on procedural justice and ethical investment at the expense of long-term performance. 10 If Norway’s SWF has moral faults, it is not on those grounds, but rather on grounds of global justice. All of these ethical achievements would be less impressive, I suggest, if Norwegians were not entitled to the revenues contained in their SWF in the first place. Should the money contained in this and similar SWFs be used to advance goals of global justice? In this paper I will suggest that it should. But before that, section 2 argues that the depiction of natural resource wealth as entirely ‘arbitrary’ or undeserved is a little too quick. Several arguments can be produced which might support the conclusion that local citizens are in fact entitled to the revenues contained in their SWF. These arguments need to be engaged with individually to establish whether they have any prospects of success. If one or more of them holds good, then using the proceeds from a SWF to benefit a state’s own citizens will be less objectionable than we might suppose. I show in section 2, however, that all these arguments fail in the Norwegian case, with the implication that the money contained in the Fund should, from the point of view of justice, be seen as vulnerable to global redistributive claims. Section 3, finally, examines the extent to which our argument should generalise to other SWFs, and offers some suggestions as to how the resources contained in many SWFs could best be used to serve global justice. 1. Norway’s Sovereign Wealth Fund The Government Pension Fund (Global) is a fund which collects various proceeds from Norwegian petroleum sales. Norway has large reserves offshore on the Norwegian Continental Shelf, the bulk of it in the North Sea. It currently produces approximately two million barrels of petroleum per day, the vast majority of it in the form of crude oil. In European terms, its production of both crude oil 4 and natural gas are only matched by Russia. 11 The Norwegian government claims ownership of all petroleum resources under its Continental Shelf, and the Fund therefore accrues revenues from taxing Norwegian oil companies, from selling exploration rights, and from the part-state-owned oil and gas company Statoil. The Pension Fund was established by the Norwegian government in 1990. By law, it is governed on behalf of Norway’s Ministry of Finance by Norges Bank Investment Management, a specialised division of the Norwegian Central Bank. Despite its title the Fund holds not pension funds, but, principally, general stocks bought with petroleum revenues – all of them in foreign currencies - with a smaller proportion of its assets comprised of overseas real estate holdings. The Fund is the second-largest SWF in the world, second only to the Abu Dhabi Investment Authority, which it is expected to outstrip in coming decades. As of the last quarter of 2012, its value was 3,723,000,000,000 Norwegian Krone, or 672 billion US dollars, and its size is expected to almost double by the end of this decade. 12 Its performance has not always been the best, precisely since its Council on Ethics holds to firm principles of accountability and ethical investing. 13 Nevertheless, it now holds a little over 1 percent of the total value of global equity markets. Successive Norwegian administrations have affirmed their intention to use the money contained in the Fund to save for the future, and to smooth out vulnerability to fluctuating commodity prices and foreign exchange rates. It is, moreover, feared that spending the revenues from petroleum sales as it came in would fuel rapid inflation, and result in an unfavourable exchange rate which would then damage other native industries. Levelling the expenditure of petroleum revenues over the long term should avoid such problems. A ‘fiscal rule’ dictates that no more than 4% of the returns on the Fund should be used for government expenditure in any given year. The Fund, as suggested in the Introduction to this paper, has been unusually vigilant in avoiding investment in companies associated with human rights abuses, companies which are involved in the arms trade, and which are associated with very harmful effects on the environment. 14 It has also shown a degree of interest, as befits a Fund which derives its wealth from fossil fuel production, in encouraging environmentally-friendly business practices. 15 But the Fund has also shown an unusually explicit concern with issues of distributive justice. Its declared concern is to ensure that future generations of Norwegians are able to enjoy the same very high standard of living as the Norwegians of the present. Although the final form of its expenditure has yet to be decided – and the details are the subject of on-going political debate – there is broad consensus that the priority should be insulating Norway’s ageing population from the looming pensions crisis facing many mature welfare states: hence the otherwise puzzling ‘Government Pension Fund’ element of its formal title. 5 But from the moral point of view, do the Norwegian people have a claim to its wealth? The idea that Norwegians in thirty or fifty years’ time ought to enjoy standards of living no worse than Norwegians presently do – that current generations should not fritter away the windfall of North Sea gas and oil - sounds like an admirable one. But it would, presumably, be considerably less admirable if Norwegians are presently enjoying a standard of living to which they are not fully entitled, or if this project of intergenerational justice is to be bankrolled using resource wealth to which Norwegians have weak or non-existent claims from the point of view of justice. In the next section I address just how strong or weak Norwegians’ entitlements to the money contained in their SWF might be. 2. Assessing Norwegian Claims over the Fund’s Natural Resource Wealth The argument that the distribution of natural resources is morally arbitrary is commonplace in the literature on global justice, but it is a little too quick. It tells us, in effect, that since no-one created natural resources (which is, for many, precisely why we define them as natural resources 16 ), and since no-one did anything to bring about their haphazard allocation across the globe, then no-one has any special claims on them. Our claims on them must, to the contrary, be symmetrical. But even if it is the case that particular communities have not created natural resources, this does not establish that communities have done nothing to generate special claims over them in the real world. Imagine we know that two communities began with equal shares of coal, but one community has frivolously burned its own share up. The current distribution between the two countries then begins to looks something other than purely arbitrary. Even if communities have not created their resources, they may have conserved or protected them, or indeed laboured over them in ways that have made them more valuable. Others, to the contrary, may have squandered, neglected or degraded theirs. Consider, alternatively, that a particular resource holds a special cultural or symbolic significance for a particular community (imagine, for instance, the great significance of Ayers Rock - or Uluru - for aboriginal Australians). Are theorists of justice too quick to treat natural resources as interchangeable goods to be distributed between us all, or should we accept that some agents have claims on particular resources? I suggest, in fact, that there are three reasons why we might believe that any given agent – which could in principle mean an individual or a community – has a special claim over particular natural resources. First, it might be the case that they have done something to significantly increase its value. In some cases we can say that a resource would not be the resource it is – or at least that 6 its economic value would be lower – unless a particular agent had acted on it by excavating it, refining it, or otherwise transforming it. When this is the case, it produces what we can call a special claim from improvement. Second, someone might have formed central life-plans or projects which are dependent upon secure and continuing access to a particular resource. Think of Hindus devoted to scattering the ashes of their dead on the water of the River Ganges, for example: for them, no other water can simply be substituted as a support for that project; it is that water which has special significance to them and which they desire continued access to. Where this is the case, it produces what we can call a special claim from attachment. Third – and this argument especially applies to collectives such as states or, potentially, indigenous communities – it might be the case that without control over a particular resource or set of resources a community would no longer be able to exercise effective self-determination. And if we have reason to value collective self-determination we will have reason, in turn, to allow at least some communities to control at least some of their resources. Any or all of these three arguments could potentially give us reason to reserve rights over particular resources for specific individuals or communities. Those reasons would then need to be balanced against – and might plausibly constrain - the broader claims of global justice which focus on the symmetrical general claims which all of us have on natural resources. The question that concerns us in this section, though, is whether any of them apply to the case of Norway’s SWF, such that they might over-ride any calls for global redistribution. Improvement Some nationalist theorists – including, most prominently, David Miller - have suggested that individual nations might deserve (at least some of) their resource wealth if they have, as a community, laboured over it and in so doing increased its value. 17 One obvious way of improving resources would be to change their properties so as to make them more useful for agriculture, industry or energy production. Raw materials might be smelted, or hardened, or purified and afterwards – because of their greater usefulness - command higher prices. To count as improvements, we expect any such activities to result in increases in market value. Thus since extracting or transporting resources can also lead to increases in economic value, such activities are plausible sources of special claims too. Perhaps this provides a basis on which Norway might have a claim over the money contained within its SWF. The market value of refined petroleum products such as gasoline and kerosene is notably higher than that of crude oil, for instance. And Norwegian companies refine much of its own crude oil before selling it on global markets. Even where 7 petroleum is sold in its unrefined state, Norwegian companies may have sunk considerable money into locating, extracting and transporting it. Surely this must generate a rather strong claim on the proceeds? There has been considerable debate, within the literature on global justice, on how such claims should be limited. For instance, is it just for agents to appropriate, improve and potentially sell on just whatever resources they can get their hands on? What about others who are less quick to appropriate? Or should we observe some kind of constraint or ‘proviso’ on appropriation? One view on this issue is that we ought not appropriate so many natural resources that we leave others unable to meet their basic needs. 18 Another would be that whenever we appropriate a greater than equal share, we owe others compensation. 19 But we do not, in fact, need to settle this thorny question, because it is less than certain that an outstanding claim from improvement exists in the first place in the Norwegian case. Consider just what a claim from improvement is a claim to. Though this is again contentious, the most persuasive answer, I would suggest, is that when an agent increases the market value of a resource they generate an entitlement to that increased value. If a quantity of crude oil is worth $10 but after I extract or transport or refine it is worth $15, then it is plausible to suggest that what I have earned a claim over is the additional $5 of value. Whereas I did nothing to create the original $10 of value, the increased value is in some important sense attributable to my actions. That, in any case, is the claim made by Miller, as well as by several contemporary scholars of Locke, and I suggest that it is a plausible one. 20 In a reasonably competitive market with multiple buyers and sellers, economic theory tells us we can assume that allowing me to retain $5 will see me recouping the marginal costs of production plus normal profits. The components of refined oil prices will represent crude oil prices (in practice comprising roughly two-thirds of total refined oil prices), plus the costs, including profits, of refining and transportation. Of course in reality there may be a third component of prices. In practice markets may be uncompetitive in the sense that a few sellers artificially restrict supply, driving up commodity prices and thereby gaining what economists call ‘scarcity rents’ in the process. Perhaps crude oil costs $10, total costs are $5, but sellers hold out for a price of $25, thereby achieving ‘rents’ of $10. World oil markets have frequently exhibited such behaviour. But economists and political philosophers have tended to agree that such scarcity rents are inefficient, unearned, and ideal targets for taxation. Recall, now, that the money diverted into the Norwegian Fund has two sources. In one case, revenue streams are gained when Norway sells exploration rights over its non-improved crude oil. In this scenario it is not easy to see how any improvement-based claim exists, because the Norwegian state or the Norwegian people have simply done nothing to improve that oil. They have simply sold 8 pieces of paper allowing others to improve and sell that oil. In practice, of course, doing so may lead Norway to incur costs which it would be reasonable for it to recoup: even allowing others to locate and extract oil might require Norway to undertake health and safety precautions, to minimise or absorb some environmental risks, and so on. But even if Norway was allowed to recoup those costs it would be left with a very large profit on a deal which it is hard to justify on the basis of improvement. On the other hand, large sums of money are also raised by taxing the very large profits currently made by Norwegian oil companies. But these very large profits are, essentially, scarcity rents. They represent the money left after the costs of exploration, extraction, transportation and, if applicable, refining. As such there is no good moral claim on them either. That is precisely why Norway has seen fit to tax such large and unearned profits and in so doing to share that wealth with the Norwegian people. But the question at stake in this paper is why it is the Norwegian people who should be the recipients of such revenues, as opposed to anyone else. The argument from improvement does not provide any answer to that question, although the remaining two arguments conceivably might. Attachment Sometimes access to natural resources is crucial to projects which are in turn deeply important to people, and indeed to the way in which they understand their own identities. If I consider myself a fisherman first and foremost but am deprived of access to fish, a project which is crucial to my life is disrupted and before long I will experience a kind of dissonance in believing myself to be a fisherman but not, in fact, fishing. If we have reasons of justice to take seriously the projects which people are most deeply invested in – and a number of accounts of justice will offer us reasons for taking them seriously – we have a reason to favour continuing access to natural resources that people are attached to. 21 It has been thought that this provides a further reason for granting resource rights to communities such as nations. On David Miller’s account, nations do not only labour physically over their resources, thereby increasing their economic value. They also incorporate them into their national projects, imaginations and histories, so that some particular resources come to be crucial props for communal identification and come to have, in that sense, great symbolic value to them in particular. Where this happens, we have a reason to allow such communities to continue to control the resources in question. 22 Crucially, we ought to consider such claims where the attachment is to a particular token of a resource – not to trees in general, for instance, but to these trees. Not to water in general, but to the water in this river. What we are looking to ground, in attachment-based accounts, are rights over particular rather than generic 9 resources, and to do so we need an argument about why particular rather than generic resources are necessary for an important project to come to fruition. Attachment-based claims are perfectly coherent, and good examples of attachment are available which give us reason to endorse granting resource rights to members of some communities. Such claims may not establish that people are entitled to more resources than others, but they may provide an answer to the question of which resources they are entitled to. Some communities are deeply attached to resources (or to the integrity of the land they are contained in), and sending outsiders in to mine these resources would rob them of something they value and disrupt or destroy projects to which they are deeply committed. Egalitarians therefore need a method for accommodating those attachments (a method which I provide elsewhere). 23 Might attachment provide a reason why Norwegians should be able to retain the assets contained in the Fund? That seems highly unlikely. It might well be that Norwegians are attached to the petroleum contained off their Western coast; we can afford to remain neutral on that. But the Fund is made up not of petroleum, but from the proceeds of selling petroleum to the highest bidder. If that petroleum was so non-substitutably important to Norwegians, we have to wonder why they did so. I suggest that other attachment-based accounts will be driven to the same conclusion. Avery Kolers has recently suggested, rather robustly, that there is a strong claim to control resources – indeed to disregard any countervailing claims of global justice – wherever those resources are not being treated as mere commodities. 24 But since Norway has already decided to extract, transform and sell its petroleum such an argument cannot begin. It is treating its petroleum as a mere commodity, a source of revenue alone. It is perfectly plausible, of course, that the Norwegian people have structured their plans and expectations around control over the money in the Fund (see section 3). Perhaps the Fund will allow Norwegians to more securely pursue projects to which they are broadly committed – in particular, the pursuit of a variety of (moderate) social democracy which avoids the excesses of the Anglo-American model, and which might in turn allow Norwegians to enjoy pursuits they are deeply attached to individually. But it is not clear that money is the kind of thing one can become attached to in the sense required to generate a special claim, as opposed to a general one. In supporting these Norwegian projects just any money would do, and not only this money. Many other communities, for that matter, would be very pleased to have such funds at their disposal. We still appear to lack a reason why Norwegians should be entitled to the money in the Fund, and not anyone else. 10 Self-determination Our third argument is rather different. It suggests that regardless of whether states have either improved or become attached to specific resources, we should grant them control over natural resources if we are committed to the idea of national self-determination. As Margaret Moore suggests, it is hard to see how any community could be properly self-determining if it didn’t have the authority to make decisions about how resources can or cannot be used, exploited and so on. 25 And international law does indeed grant individual states ‘permanent sovereignty’ over the natural resources contained within their territories on something like this basis. 26 Invoking self-determination cannot, of course, be a conversation-stopper. Presumably we will want to know just why self-determination is valuable, and if we are persuaded that it is valuable we will then want more detail on just how much control over how many resources it truly demands. Self-determination cannot, presumably, mean that communities can use their resources in just any way they please and to heck with the ecological consequences. Moreover if one community controlled all of the world’s resources whilst other communities went starving, a mere appeal to the value of self-determination would not be the end of the story. Why, then, is self-determination valuable, and how much does it truly demand by way of resource control? The best available defence of territorial rights on the part of individual nation-states is probably the ‘functionalist’ argument, which states that we should value self-determination because self-determining communities are able to protect the basic rights of their citizens. 27 If there were no political communities capable of preserving order and securing minimal services, our basic rights would be seriously threatened. But to deliver those minimal services, some measure of control over the natural resources within a state’s borders appears to be in order. It is hard to see how a state could secure the basic rights of its citizens, for instance, without access to freshwater. However, what is striking about this argument is that it demands relatively little in the way of resource control. It appears to demand control over resources whenever those are necessary to secure basic rights, but to have no particular implications for natural resources which are ‘surplus’ to this. Many nation- states – including Norway – are already very effective at securing the basic rights of their citizens, and clearly possess resource wealth above and beyond what is required to protect them. The functionalist argument gives us no particular reason to leave control over such resources with local states. Indeed, if what fundamentally matters – and what drives the concern with self- determination in the first place – is that people’s basic rights are secured, it may make sense to use such surpluses to help states which currently struggle to meet the basic rights of their citizens. 28 11 That might not be the end of the story from the point of view of self-determination, however. Even if control over a surplus of resources is not necessary for self-determining states to perform their core functions, the right to self-determination might still be violated if outsiders simply walked onto Norwegian territory in order to re-appropriate resources. Imagine a United Nations Natural Resources Taskforce descending on Norwegian territory with helicopters and siphoning off some of its oil for use in other parts of the world. Would we not say that Norway’s right to self-determination would be seriously disrupted by such incursions? Shouldn’t it be the decision of the Norwegians whether, when and under what conditions to make use of its oil? Is there any way in which Norway’s hand could be forced without seriously impairing its ability to make its own decisions, and even to protect its territorial integrity? Of course, the location of the petroleum in question many miles off the Norwegian coast might do something to alleviate concerns about territorial incursions. 29 But there will be cases in other states where the oil is buried under the ground, in which the worry would re-emerge. However we should not allow this concern to lead us to exaggerate the tension between self-determination and global justice. There are, after all, many ways of sharing the benefits arising from natural resources without actually removing those resources. When theorists of climate justice debate how much greenhouse gas each country should be able to emit, for instance, one of the things they are doing is dividing up rights to make use of carbon sinks, at least some of which – like the tropical rainforests – are contained within particular nation-states. Making use of those sinks does not require incursions onto the territory of those states. On the topic of oil, we could simply say that whenever it is that a country decides to raise money from its oil – whether by selling it or selling rights to it - it should then pay a global tax. Significantly, in the Norwegian SWF case what is at issue is not whether Norway or anyone else should extract or sell on its oil. Norway is already extracting and selling its oil on global commodity markets. The question is simply whether Norway should, as a matter of justice, then share the income derived from selling those resources. Since the basic rights of Norwegians are not at stake – and neither is its territorial integrity - concern for Norway’s self-determination as a community does not give us reasonable grounds for resisting the conclusion that it should share the money flowing into its Fund. The claim that the distribution of natural resource wealth is morally arbitrary, that great unearned advantages are enjoyed by many countries, and that there is nothing much, from the point of view of justice, to be said in favour of leaving resources where they are is too quick. It has become apparent in recent years that there are sometimes cases where leaving resources put makes moral 12 sense. But the Norwegian case does not appear to be one of them. On closer analysis, it actually represents a relatively straightforward case for advocates of redistribution in the interests of global justice. The three arguments considered in this section fail, in this case at least, to support local claims. In the absence of good arguments to the contrary we therefore have every reason, from the point of view of justice, to consider redistributing the financial resources contained in the Fund both plausible and desirable. 3. Sovereign Wealth Funds and Global Justice My goal in this paper has been to connect recent discussions of Sovereign Wealth Funds with debates on global justice. There are many potential targets for principles of global justice, and conceivably justice at the global level might best be served by a rather complex web of tax-and- spend schemes; according to various commentators these might include taxes on financial transactions, or environmental harms, or even political membership. 30 But the wealth contained in SWFs, I have suggested, bears examination in the same category. Theorists of global justice therefore ought to pay attention to their potential to fund progress towards global justice. At the same time, those interested in the role of SWFs in the contemporary economy should widen their discussions of the ethical implications of such Funds, and begin to debate their potential to deliver on projects of global, and not purely national, justice. The question remains, of course, of exactly which account of global justice we ought to favour. If we were to tax the wealth contained in at least some SWFs in the interests of global justice, say, should we target the revenues at eradicating severe poverty, as Thomas Pogge would have it? Pogge’s view has to date endorsed the taxation of natural resources at the point of extraction, but the argument I have presented in this paper suggests that supporters of Pogge’s view would do well to (also) examine the potential of SWFs to assist in poverty alleviation. Strikingly, the Norwegian Fund for instance contains roughly double the (annual) amount of money which Pogge reckons necessary to eradicate severe poverty worldwide. 31 My own view is that we should set our sights even higher, and try to minimise global inequalities. Taxing wealth derived from natural resource sales – including the money contained in many SWFs – offers one means of doing so. But a fuller defence of that view would be the subject of another paper. There is also a question about how widely the lessons drawn from the Norwegian case generalise. The same conclusions, I suggest, will follow for other wealthy countries with SWFs 13 derived from selling natural resource wealth. In the case of poor countries which happen to be resource-rich, global justice might recommend that we leave revenues where they are, if doing so proved to be an effective means of tackling serious poverty. But this is a large if, since many resource-rich but otherwise poor countries have proven very ineffective at using the proceeds of natural resource sales to seriously attack domestic poverty. That is one important lesson, for example, of Leif Wenar’s recent work on the international resource trade. 32 But Wenar’s suggestion is that we cease to trade with illegitimate regimes seeking to sell natural resources from under the noses of their citizens. His account is silent on the question of how the funds already gained from this morally repugnant trade should be governed or disbursed between citizens. This is a question on which we urgently need guidance. Most likely, even if we should favour the use of these particular SWFs to tackle domestic poverty, there is a strong argument for independent, transparent and accountable governance of such SWFs, accurate public reporting of resource revenues, and mission-statements aimed much more clearly at spreading the wealth derived from natural resources. As for the many natural resource-derived Funds which are managed on behalf of wealthier countries, there is a clear argument in favour of using some form of global taxation in order to better share their wealth. My goal is not to provide an account of how, institutionally, any such taxation scheme should be organized. But I will, briefly, indicate some ways in which the revenues which could be derived from such taxation might be best spent. There is considerable resistance from those currently tasked with managing SWFs to disbursing their assets to individual citizens, because of a fear that dividends will simply be ‘blown’ on short-term consumption rather than long- term investment, and we might expect resistance, as a result, to the idea that money should be spent by way of simple transfers to the global poor. 33 At the global level, we might also fear that money remitted to poorly-governed and imperfectly democratic countries would be mis-spent, exacerbating the ‘resource curse’ to which those countries are already often subject. This concern, of course, provides no objection to using those assets in the interests of global rather than domestic justice. If it is a valid concern it counsels, in both the domestic and the global case, in favour of using the money contained in SWFs to sustain longer-term investment programs. There are, in fact, a number of global infrastructure projects that could provide appropriate targets for such money. There is no particular reason why these should be projects connected with natural resources, and money could no doubt usefully be spent on developing educational infrastructure in developing countries, enhancing health-care provision or combatting tropical diseases or HIV. But there are also a number of projects more closely connected with natural resources that would seek to enhance local capacity, resource conservation and long-term economic development. Money could 14 be spent, for instance, on developing capacity to harness rainwater and hence to reduce dependence on unsustainable forms of irrigation in agriculture. It could be spent on developing (and spreading) green technologies to reduce the dependence of emerging economies on fossil fuel use. Or it could be spent on funding the protection of terrestrial carbon sinks such as rainforests. I have argued elsewhere that there is a pressing claim of global justice that the costs (including opportunity costs) of protecting rainforests should be shared between all of us and not borne solely by those who happen to have rainforests within their territories, and who are therefore asked to sacrifice their own economic development in the (broader) interests of the security of the climate. 34 If we believe that countries with rainforests should refrain from cutting them down (and we may well be right to demand this), we should nevertheless be prepared to investigate opportunities for spreading the costs of such sacrifices more fairly. Taxing natural resource-based SWFs would provide an excellent source for the major flows of revenue that would be required to make such ‘payments for protection.’ Finally, let us return briefly to the Norwegian case which has been discussed at length. Though I have singled out Norway’s Fund as an example of the kind of SWF that theorists of global justice would do well to devote more attention to, singling this Fund out should not be taken to mean, of course, that it would be fair to target Norway’s Fund to the exclusion of others. The point is not that we should simply raid Norway’s Fund to gain money with which to tackle global injustices, however pressing those goals might be. There are two reasons for being sceptical about that idea. First, we might believe that Norwegians would only be obliged to give away their money if they knew that others would be targeted in the same way. It is an issue of considerable controversy within normative theory whether agents have a duty to ‘take up the slack’ when it comes to justice – to take upon themselves, that is, additional duties to make up for the inaction of others. But certainly some are sceptical that such duties exist. 35 Second, we might consider that Norway has developed legitimate expectations to use the money contained in its Fund, given that up to now, of course, there has been no scheme in place for taxing SWFs. 36 Allowing Norwegians to keep the money in their Fund would again be controversial, because it will be a matter of dispute how heavily we should weigh any legitimate expectations against the goals of ameliorating crushing injustices elsewhere. As Henry George once provocatively argued, it is no straightforward thing to say to the poor of the world that, since the rich have become used to excluding them from the world’s resources, they should be allowed to continue to do so. The needs of the poor presumably also have some weight, unaccustomed as they are to having them satisfied. 37 15 I do not aim to resolve these debates, though, because as I said it is not my intention to claim that we should target Norway’s Fund alone. Still, even if it is not fair to single out particular countries, we can legitimately attempt to offer moral persuasion. It might not be fair to require Norway to give its money away in the absence of similar actions from others. But we might still agree that it would be desirable if they did, and we might also agree that it is perfectly legitimate for theorists of global justice to try to persuade them to place more emphasis on global, and not solely national, justice priorities. Here it is both welcome and worth noting that the Norwegian Fund, unusually among SWFs, has already made some tentative steps in the direction of global justice, in seeking to steer some investment towards green technologies and to encourage corporate ecological responsibility. It has encountered both praise and criticism for doing so, insofar as it has reached a shifting compromise between ‘ethical investment’ and maximising returns. But we might try to encourage the organizing council of the Fund to be more bold in funding such projects even where the expected returns are far from optimal. Even if schemes for taxing SWFs are unlikely to come to fruition in the near future, making a significant contribution towards the development of green technologies and subsidising their introduction in developing countries would be one way in which the activities of Norway’s Fund – or indeed any given Fund - could be made more compatible with goals of global justice. 1 See Ashby Monk, ‘Recasting the Sovereign Wealth Fund Debate: Trust, Legitimacy and Governance,’ New Political Economy 14.4 (2009): 451-68; Edwin Truman, ‘Sovereign Wealth Funds: the Need for More Accountability and Transparency,’ Peterson Institute Policy Brief (2009). 2 Amy Keller, ‘Sovereign Wealth Funds: Trustworthy Investors or Vehicles of Strategic Ambition?’ Georgetown Journal of Law and Public Policy 7.1 (2009): 333-72. 3 Angela Cummine, ‘Overcoming Dividend Skepticism: Why the World’s Sovereign Wealth Funds Are Not Paying Basic Income Dividends,’ Basic Income Studies 6.1 (2011): 1-17. 4 Witness, for instance, the 2011 acquisition of the Paris Saint-Germain football franchise by the Qatar Investment Authority. 5 Ronald Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue: the Theory and Practice of Equality (London: Harvard University Press, 2000). 16 6 There is considerable controversy, of course, about whether we owe duties of distributive to people outside of our own communities, and of what type. This paper is primarily targeted at those who believe we do have such duties. But for an overview of the relevant positions – defended both by those convinced that we have stringent duties of global justice, and those who are sceptical about their existence – see Chris Armstrong, Global Distributive Justice: An Introduction (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012). 7 Charles Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979); Thomas Pogge, World Poverty and Human Rights (Cambridge: Polity, 2002); Mathias Risse, On Global Justice (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2012). Hillel Steiner also defends a global tax on natural resources, to be paid wherever anyone appropriates an above per capita equal share. Steiner, ‘Just Taxation and International Redistribution,’ in I. Shapiro and L. Brilmayer (eds) Global Justice (New York: New York University Press, 1999), pp. 171-91. 8 Mehmet Caner and Thomas Grennes, ‘Sovereign Wealth Funds: the Norwegian Experience,’ The World Economy 33.4 (2010): 597-614. 9 Kristin Halvorsen, ‘Norway's Sovereign Fund Sets an Ethical Example,’ Financial Times, 14 th February 2008; Simon Chesterman, ‘The Turn to Ethics: Disinvestment from Multinational Corporations for Human Rights Violations - The Case of Norway's Sovereign Wealth Fund,’ American University International Law Review 23.3 (2008): 577-616. 10 Gordon Clark and Ashby Monk, ‘The Norwegian Government Pension Fund: Ethics over Efficiency,’ Rotman International Journal of Pension Management 3.1 (2010): 14-19. 11 http://www.eia.gov/countries/cab.cfm?fips=NO (US Energy Information Administration, accessed 14 th February 2013). 12 According to the Norges Bank’s own calculations: see http://www.nbim.no/en/About- us/Government-Pension-Fund-Global/ 13 See the Council on Ethics website: http://www.regjeringen.no/en/sub/styrer-rad- utvalg/ethics_council.html?id=434879. 14 Chesterman, ‘The Turn to Ethics.’ 15 Danyel Reiche, Sovereign Wealth Funds as a New Instrument of Climate Protection Policy? Wuppertal Institute for Climate, Environment and Energy Working Paper 173e (2008). As Reiche notes, the Fund has not only dis-invested in companies with poor environmental records, but sought to exert pressure on companies campaigning against environmental protection legislation in countries like the US. Its leverage in this regard is attenuated by its policy of not holding more than 10% of the equity of any company. 16 Risse, On Global Justice. http://www.eia.gov/countries/cab.cfm?fips=NO http://www.nbim.no/en/About-us/Government-Pension-Fund-Global/ http://www.nbim.no/en/About-us/Government-Pension-Fund-Global/ http://www.regjeringen.no/en/sub/styrer-rad-utvalg/ethics_council.html?id=434879 http://www.regjeringen.no/en/sub/styrer-rad-utvalg/ethics_council.html?id=434879 17 17 David Miller, National Responsibility and Global Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), at 217-8. Miller’s argument here applies explicitly to rights over land, but he extends the argument to cover natural resources in his paper ‘Territorial Rights: Concept and Justification,’ Political Studies 60.2 (2011): 252-68. 18 Risse, On Global Justice. 19 Hillel Steiner, An Essay on Rights (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994). 20 Miller, National Responsibility, p. 218. For a Lockean analysis, see e.g. Gopal Sreenivasan, The Limits of Lockean Rights in Property (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995). 21 Chris Armstrong, ‘Justice and Attachment to Natural Resources,’ Journal of Political Philosophy (2013, EarlyView). 22 Miller, National Responsibility, at pp. 218-9. 23 Armstrong, ‘Justice and Attachment.’ 24 Avery Kolers, ‘Justice, Territory and Natural Resources,’ Political Studies 60.2 (2012): 269-86. I critically examine Kolers’s account in ‘Resources, Rights and Global Justice: A Response to Kolers,’ Political Studies (2013, EarlyView). 25 Margaret Moore, ‘Natural Resources, Territorial Right and Global Distributive Justice,’ Political Theory 40.1 92012): 84-107, at 88. 26 Within the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, for instance, the clause on ‘permanent sovereignty’ over natural resources is contained within Article 1, which concerns self- determination. See http://www2.ohchr.org/english/law/ccpr.htm. 27 For a functionalist defence of territorial rights, see Anna Stilz, ‘Nations, States and Territory,’ Ethics 121.3 (2011): 572-601. 28 It may matter morally, of course, just why they struggle. On some accounts, if a community culpably failed to meet the basic rights of its citizens even after being given assistance from overseas, then the obligation to continue to provide such assistance might diminish. For two influential discussions of the grounds and limits of outsiders to help poor communities meet their citizens’ basic rights, see John Rawls, The Law of Peoples with ‘The Idea of Public Reason Revisited’ (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1999), and David Miller, National Responsibility, chapter 9. 29 See also Christopher Heath Wellman, ‘Political Legitimacy and Territorial Rights,’ unpublished ms, at p. 25. 30 For an overview of such proposals, see Chris Armstrong, ‘Proposals for Distributive Institutions,’ in D. Moellendorf and H. Widdows (eds) Acumen Handbook of Global Ethics (forthcoming 2014). 31 Pogge, World Poverty and Human Rights. 32 Leif Wenar, ‘Clean Trade in Natural Resources,’ Ethics & International Affairs 25.1 (2011): 27-39. http://www2.ohchr.org/english/law/ccpr.htm 18 33 Cummine, ‘Overcoming Dividend Skepticism,’ at 4-8. 34 Chris Armstrong, ‘Sharing the Costs of Rainforest Protection,’ unpublished manuscript. 35 For a sceptical view about duties to take up the slack, see David Miller, ‘Taking Up the Slack? Responsibility and Justice in Situations of Partial Compliance,’ in C. Knight and Z. Stemplowska (eds) Responsibility and Distributive Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011), pp. 230-45. For a view that there can be such duties, see Zofia Stemplowska, ‘Doing More Than One’s Fair Share,’ unpublished manuscript. 36 A claim based on legitimate expectations might resemble an argument from attachment, but it would be different in form because - as I suggested in section 2 - attachment-based claims are claims to particular tokens or a resource, and not to fungible or substitutable goods like money. 37 Henry George, Progress and Poverty (London: The Henry George Foundation, 1932 [1881], at p. 259. work_buvuyxz5y5fbtd6y3frqvpqpme ---- Action heritage: research, communities, social justice Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=rjhs20 Download by: [University of Sheffield] Date: 21 June 2017, At: 02:00 International Journal of Heritage Studies ISSN: 1352-7258 (Print) 1470-3610 (Online) Journal homepage: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rjhs20 Action heritage: research, communities, social justice Robert Johnston & Kimberley Marwood To cite this article: Robert Johnston & Kimberley Marwood (2017): Action heritage: research, communities, social justice, International Journal of Heritage Studies, DOI: 10.1080/13527258.2017.1339111 To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/13527258.2017.1339111 © 2017 The Author(s). Published by Informa UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis Group Published online: 12 Jun 2017. Submit your article to this journal Article views: 68 View related articles View Crossmark data http://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=rjhs20 http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rjhs20 http://www.tandfonline.com/action/showCitFormats?doi=10.1080/13527258.2017.1339111 http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/13527258.2017.1339111 http://www.tandfonline.com/action/authorSubmission?journalCode=rjhs20&show=instructions http://www.tandfonline.com/action/authorSubmission?journalCode=rjhs20&show=instructions http://www.tandfonline.com/doi/mlt/10.1080/13527258.2017.1339111 http://www.tandfonline.com/doi/mlt/10.1080/13527258.2017.1339111 http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1080/13527258.2017.1339111&domain=pdf&date_stamp=2017-06-12 http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1080/13527258.2017.1339111&domain=pdf&date_stamp=2017-06-12 InternatIonal Journal of HerItage StudIeS, 2017 https://doi.org/10.1080/13527258.2017.1339111 Action heritage: research, communities, social justice Robert Johnstona and Kimberley Marwoodb adepartment of archaeology, university of Sheffield, Sheffield, uK; bacademic and learning Services, university of Sheffield, Sheffield, uK ABSTRACT Societies are unequal and unjust to varying degrees and heritage practitioners unavoidably work with, perpetuate and have the potential to change these inequalities. This article proposes a new framework for undertaking heritage research that can be applied widely and purposefully to achieve social justice, and which we refer to as action heritage. Our primary sources are semi-structured conversations we held with some of the participants in three heritage projects in South Yorkshire, UK: members of a hostel for homeless young people, a primary school, and a local history group. We examine ‘disruptions’ in the projects to understand the repositioning of the participants as researchers. The disruptions include introducing a scrapbook for personal stories in the homeless youth project and giving the school children opportunities to excavate alongside professional archaeologists. These disruptions reveal material and social inequalities through perceptible changes in how the projects were oriented and how the participants thought about the research. We draw on this empirical research and theorisations of social justice to develop a new framework for undertaking co-produced research. Action heritage is ‘undisciplinary’ research that privileges process over outcomes, and which achieves parity of participation between academic and community-based researchers through sustained recognition and redistribution. Introduction At the beginning of a heritage project in which one of us (KM) participated, a class of primary-age school children (10 and 11 years) were asked the question ‘Are you researchers?’ All said ‘no’. After a week spent finding out about the history of the place where they lived and the people who had lived there, the same class were again asked the question: ‘Are you researchers?’ Without hesitation, they enthusiastically replied ‘yes’. Our article is a consideration of this transformation and what it means to participate in heritage research and be recognised as a researcher. We will propose a new framework for undertaking heritage research, which we term action heritage. We develop an argument for action heritage using the example that opened this article, a school in Rotherham, UK, and two further community heritage projects in nearby Sheffield. All three were part of a wider project funded by the UK’s Arts and Humanities Research Council (AHRC) called Research for Community Heritage (RCH) (Vergunst et al. 2017). RCH was supported through the AHRC’s Connected Communities programme, which explores new © 2017 the author(s). Published by Informa uK limited, trading as taylor & francis group. this is an open access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons attribution license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited. KEYWORDS Heritage; community; participatory research; inequality; recognition ARTICLE HISTORY received 20 March 2017 accepted 28 May 2017 CONTACT robert Johnston r.johnston@sheffield.ac.uk OPEN ACCESS http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ mailto: r.johnston@sheffield.ac.uk http://www.tandfonline.com http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1080/13527258.2017.1339111&domain=pdf 2 R. JOHNSTON AND K. MARWOOD humanities-based approaches to deepening our understanding of communities (Facer and Enright 2016). For RCH, Connected Communities joined with the UK’s Heritage Lottery Fund (HLF) and encouraged community organisations to work with academics and develop year-long heritage projects. RCH at the University of Sheffield involved academic researchers from a wide range of disciplines (including archaeology, education, history, linguistics, literature and music) working closely with 14 community organisations. Through RCH, we aimed to work with organisations that had not previously engaged in heritage research, whether due to lack of capacity or a sense that it was ‘not for them’. By taking this approach, we were shifting the focus for collaborative research away from established heritage groups that were already confident and effective in gaining HLF funding and working alongside professional heritage organisations. These established organisations include local history and archaeology societies, and ‘friends of ’ groups that look after cherished places such as parks and cemeteries. By shifting our attention towards groups that had not previously engaged with heritage research, we found ourselves working with communities that were underrepresented in our university and in the community her- itage discourse in our region: for example, Muslim and Hindu women’s organisations, a mountain rescue team, a refugee support charity and a homeless hostel for young people. Alongside partnering with non-traditional heritage groups, we also sought inclusive ways of col- laborating during the research. We adopted a co-production research model that allowed multiple voices to be heard and respected as the research progressed, and that recognised and benefited from expertise across all the constituencies who participated in the research. Co-production has both a specific meaning for certain fields within the social sciences (e.g. the delivery of public services: Ostrom 1996) and is employed as a catch-all term for a wide spectrum of participatory and collabo- rative research models (Facer and Enright 2016, 82–89). Because of their wide variety of objectives (although all within the field of heritage), our projects followed the latter course and worked within a broad formulation of co-production rather than its more specific definition. Applying this method, we partnered with community groups from the inception of the projects, we addressed the barriers that we perceived were impeding participation from community organisations, and we created a wide variety of outputs for diverse audiences (such as videos, interpretation panels, booklets and music) rather than prioritising academic articles or conference presentations. At first inexperienced and naive, we gradually became more skilled though rarely comfortable in our attempts at co-production. An insight that emerged for us was that researching heritage shaped how we – both university and community participants – understood ourselves and our agency within the social relations of the project and with respect to wider society. The practices and processes of researching became a means of enfranchising participants, and of revealing and contesting inequal- ities within and beyond the projects. Through RCH, we personally began understanding research in new ways and subsequently sought to do research differently: ‘critical understanding leads to critical action’ (Freire 2002, 44). We use this article to explore the act of co-researching with three distinct communities and their involvement with RCH. We begin by tracing the links between heritage, social action and social justice. We then explore these links in conversation with our co-researchers from three projects. We conclude with a new framework for undertaking heritage research, called action heritage. Action heritage pri- oritises processes rather than outcomes, and aims to increase social justice by widening participation in research and challenging the inequalities in how we do research. Heritage as action, as socially active research As a discipline and practice heritage has changed fundamentally from its more traditional associations with rather narrow nationalistic, institutional, and bucolic manifestations of the past (Harrison 2013). While these manifestations of heritage still exist, and in certain places still predominate, the term ‘heritage’ has been appropriated in many more settings. Heritage is now acknowledged as a resource distributed across society, with working-class heritage, community heritage, Black and South Asian INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HERITAGE STUDIES 3 heritage, amongst the more fragmented geographies of contemporary heritage discourse in the UK and internationally (Graham, Ashworth, and Tunbridge 2016). There is a further shift in thinking that interests us: heritage is no longer conceived as stable and uniform, and is instead ‘related to human action and agency, and as an instrument of cultural power’ (Harvey 2001, 327). Heritage is a process involving actions such as remembering, commemorating, communicating and passing on knowledge and memories. ‘Doing heritage’ does not simply refer to the preservation or celebration of the past, it also involves negotiating and making decisions about the past in the present (Heritage Decisions Research Team 2015). The inherited past is part of political, community and personal discourses in the present, and it is a structuring condition of our future. It is a ‘social and cultural process that mediates a sense of cultural, social and political change’ (Smith 2006, 84). In these terms, heritage can be both a condition of social action and a form of social action: if heritage can be a form of cultural capital and a way of connecting people with each other and the environment that surrounds them, the promotion of heritage or involvement in heritage can be considered to be a form of social action. (Harrison 2010, 245) It is a small step to move from recognising heritage as social action to specifically directing that action towards social justice (e.g. Byrne 2008; Newman and McLean 1998; Sandell and Nightingale 2013). Indeed, it has been argued that there is a moral imperative to address issues of economic and social inequality through heritage activities (Kiddey 2017; Smith, Shackel, and Campbell 2011, 1). For example, retrieving and celebrating working-class heritage is ‘intrinsically linked to projects of protest and social justice’ because of the historical suppression and erasure of these histories (Smith, Shackel, and Campbell 2011, 13). In an archaeological setting, the Colorado Coalfield War Project exhumed the class struggle of the Ludlow massacre to raise awareness of the present-day struggles of working families (McGuire 2008, 189). The massacre occurred in 1914, when the Colorado National Guard attacked a temporary encampment housing 1200 workers and their families who had been evicted from their company properties. The archaeological project used students’ participation in archaeology to teach them about the importance of labour rights, class relations, and their rights as workers. Such political activism is intrinsic to the application of various strands of participatory research in archae- ology, museums and heritage more widely (e.g. Atalay 2012; McGhee 2012). Participatory research involves community and institutional participants collaborating either equally on projects or with community participants taking the lead. Such research has particularly strong roots in postcolonial contexts where indigenous rights have come to the fore as a response to deep-rooted and stark struc- tural and value-based inequalities. Indigenous heritage offers case studies where the dissonant qualities of heritage are irrefutable and the inequalities in recognition and representation are easily visible. Outside these settings, in western Europe for example, the divisions between ‘experts’ and ‘communities’ remain valid even if the lessons learnt from indigenous heritage projects cannot be directly translated and applied (Smith and Waterton 2009, 141). By way of response, Laurajane Smith and Emma Waterton have worked together on a sub- tler theorisation of how social inequalities can be challenged through heritage policies and practices (Smith and Waterton 2009; Waterton and Smith 2010). They largely draw upon Nancy Fraser’s work and specifically her status model of recognition and its application to social justice (e.g. Fraser 2000, 2003; Lister 2008). Political theorists use recognition as a normative concept to mean the recognition of differences in identity and status between groups within society. Fraser argues that addressing inequal- ities through the recognition of collective identities alone can lead to the simplification and reification of those identities. For example, there are now many instances in the UK and internationally where working-class communities, once under-represented in established discourse, have been foregrounded in museums and at heritage sites. While a valuable rebalancing, defining working-class heritage can also homogenise complex identities, and reify and enhance divisions between communities. Rather than addressing inequalities, representing a specific working-class heritage can marginalise groups still further from mainstream discourse. Fraser proposes an alternative to this identity model of recogni- tion. In her status model she argues for recognition through parity of participation, which addresses 4 R. JOHNSTON AND K. MARWOOD inequalities by bringing subordinated groups and individuals into social life as peers or full partners in social interaction: ‘redressing misrecognition means replacing institutionalised value patterns that impede parity of participation with ones that enable or foster it’ (Fraser 2000, 115). Laurajane  Smith and Emma  Waterton, rightly we feel, present Fraser’s theory as a strong nor- mative framework for guiding policy and practice in the management of heritage and working with communities (Smith and Waterton 2009; Waterton and Smith 2010). This framework recognises and enables parities of participation between and within communities and seeks to redress inequalities in how decisions about heritage are made and how heritage is represented and communicated. By connecting heritage with social action, theorists can explain how people who have been historically and culturally excluded can engage with heritage as a way of building a sense of their shared identity in the present (Harrison 2010, 259). While we agree with this in principle, we also identify something missing from this formulation. Forging links with the past necessarily involves communities in a process of discovering, learning and producing new understandings about their past. Heritage for social action might involve the use of unofficial heritage activities or the challenging of existing heritage practices, but heritage researchers build their counter-narratives using oral histories, archaeological discoveries and historical archives. Despite the importance of the research underpinning representations of heritage, the term ‘research’ is rarely used in heritage studies literature. Perhaps this is because it carries exclusive associations with academic and institutionalised heritage discourse. For us, RCH was about a decentring, or dispersal, of research and the acknowledgement of ‘shared epistemologies’ (Pahl and Pool 2011) between com- munity and university-based researchers. We use the remainder of this article to consider the place of research within a selection of the projects completed during RCH. Our primary sources are semi-structured focus groups we held with some of the participants in three RCH projects in Sheffield and Rotherham: a homeless hostel for young people (Roundabout); a primary school, with children aged 10–11 (Portals to the Past); and a local history group, where many of the participants are middle-aged or retired (Heeley History Workshop). We selected the three projects to be broadly representative of the different constituencies and types of projects we worked with during RCH. We chose focus group interviewing as a method because we wanted to understand a range of different experiences that participants had of research within the pro- jects, and we judged that the interactions within the groups would result in strong, multi-dimensional responses (Krueger and Casey 2009, 19, 20). We also believe that the group conversation was a logical continuation of the collaborative culture that existed during the projects – it made sense to reflect collectively on co-produced research. Our aim during the conversations was to draw out participants’ experiences of undertaking heritage research as a collaboration between community organisations and universities. Specifically, we sought accounts of where agency to undertake research resided within the projects and how if at all this agency changed during the research. Each conversation lasted around one hour, and they took place in late 2013 (within 2–3 months of the completion of the RCH projects). They were recorded and transcribed, and the participants gave their consent following research ethics processes approved by the University of Sheffield. We began the conversations with a brief introduction and then followed three lines of discussion: (1) Who was doing research and what kind of research were they doing? (2) How, if at all, was heritage different as a framing device or as a theme within these projects compared with the organisation’s usual activities? (3) What changed because of the project? We chose these as guiding topics as they addressed the status of research, researchers and heritage in the projects – in only one case (Heeley History Project) did the community group have prior experience of undertaking research on their heritage. We kept the conversations informal and allowed the sessions to be led as much by the participants’ interests as our own. We analysed the transcriptions of the conversations with qualitative analysis software using a basic thematic approach, which allowed us to identify and compare the different ways in which the participants talked about their experiences of heritage and research. INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HERITAGE STUDIES 5 Better than doing nothing Roundabout is a Sheffield-based youth charity. They maintain a hostel as an emergency or medi- um-term residency for young people who are homeless. During the HLF-funded project, one of us (KM), together with academic historians and literature specialists, helped the hostel’s residents to research the history of their hostel, which is a protected (Grade II Listed) building dating to the late 1700s. Together the team devised a series of activities that involved the young people finding out about the building, the people who lived there and the local area. The transient nature of the hostel’s residents (they normally stay for up to six weeks) meant that only a few young people participated in more than one activity. These activities included a heritage trail, trips to local heritage sites and research visits to the local studies library and the university (Figure 1). As most of the young people would not remain in the hostel to see the conclusion of the project, the research process itself was privileged above potential outputs. The primary aim was to introduce the young people to the places and practices of research rather than on achieving tangible outcomes. Our conversation with the team at Roundabout included a youth worker, the CEO, the hostel manager and the artist-facilitator employed to produce a film about the project. For Roundabout, who regularly organise activities for their residents, research formed another way to bring the young people into unfamiliar spaces, as Ben (BK), the charity’s CEO, noted: as an organisation we try and help people with their social skills and just doing things that they wouldn’t normally do, going to places they wouldn’t normally go to. the library was good, it took them to somewhere they hadn’t been before – it was personal, some people were researching their area and realised there was old pictures from their area and stuff and the university trip, again they went somewhere where they wouldn’t usually go and mix with people they wouldn’t usually mix with so they got a lot from that. (BK) It was not only the young people who, by researching, were doing ‘things they wouldn’t normally do’ and enabling access to ‘places they wouldn’t normally go’. The hostel staff and academic researchers were also on new ground: Figure 1. a visit to Sheffield local Studies library during the heritage project with roundabout youth housing charity. Source and image copyright: Justine gaubert. 6 R. JOHNSTON AND K. MARWOOD we all were researching, we weren’t trying to push the young people to do the majority of the research but it was sort of out of my comfort zone as well so definitely it was out of theirs […] I think altogether everybody contributed but the young people contributed massively as well, which was great. (RA – hostel youth worker) I had to go and learn those things as well – so that’s been for me, as a researcher, really valuable I think finding ways to do research differently but to communicate that with different people. (KM – academic researcher) These reflections draw out the discomfort that may come from working with people and in places with which we are unfamiliar: ‘because it was really intimidating for the young people, but equally I think the students were … it was out of their comfort zone’ (KM). Co-production does not necessarily start with an equality of access to resources, whether those be material or knowledge. Roundabout had clear expectations about where expertise lay, with the university providing ‘the technical stuff of where to search and how to search’, for instance, and in practice taking responsibility for devising the research activities. Using established measures of research outcomes, the project produced relatively little new knowl- edge about the hostel buildings and their former residents. We failed, for example, to locate the original deeds and owners and only found out basic details about former occupants from census data and trade directories. Yet our conversation barely touched on these aspects of the project. Instead, nearly a third of the discussion was spent considering individuals’ personal engagement with heritage and doing research: ‘this project it kind of surprised me in that a lot of the people who I thought would never get engaged did seem the most engaged’ (RA). going to that library, I don’t think any of them had gone to that library before, and certainly not into the local history bit, and you know, they might not go this year or the year after but in ten years’ time they might go and say, ‘I’m interested in my family’. (BK) By forging personal connections, the young people made the past relevant to their lives. Their research operated as a means of exploring ways to belong, placemaking and anchoring in a fluid community and was a means of drawing freshly discovered and deeply set strands back into their personal histories. The young people compiled a scrapbook to document their connections with the hostel and the heritage project. The scrapbook wove together evidence from the library and archives with the young people’s stories and their written reflections on experiences of the hostel: I think in the beginning the scrapbook talks about just the hostel and the history of the hostel and what we have found out but then further on it goes into the young people’s stories and messages, so hopefully they’ll just carry on doing that and then when people come in nearly two, three years’ time they’ll realise that there was other people in the same situation that have come from the same backgrounds as them … so hopefully it will keep evolving and getting added to. (RA) The focus on storytelling during the scrapbook sessions encouraged the young people to record their experiences using their own symbols, methods and art forms (Kindon, Pain, and Kesby 2007, 17): ‘food vouchers, cigarettes, life skills timetable … just examples of their life at the moment at Roundabout’ (RA). The participatory methods, introduced by the academics, foregrounded the links between personal experiences and the histories of the building and the community. It also provided a way to continue a reflective conversation between the young people around the theme of heritage and identity. This sense of narrative was less visible when different people took part in each of the participatory workshops. The scrapbook, on the other hand, enabled stories to unfold, to be physically layered, and to ‘speak’ to one another despite absences: they’ll have something long lasting in Roundabout other than just their file that we’ll put on the computer, they’ll have something that’s tangible, you know a letter or something that they produced in the scrapbook…I kind of made a joke to them that I would phone them up in ten years’ time and say ‘remember when you said you would be doing this by now, what are you doing?’ So it just makes them think about what they have got…their future, what they want (RA) This experience may reflect a positive impact on the participants’ well-being. In a study of the influ- ences of heritage on the well-being of hospital patients, Erica Ander and colleagues identified ‘per- sonal memories and recollections giving a renewed sense of identity’ as one explanation that patients gave for how heritage improved their well-being (Ander et al. 2013, 235). By engaging in research INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HERITAGE STUDIES 7 and reflecting on their past and present circumstances, the participants constructed hopes for their futures. As Ray said, the project encouraged the young people to look at ‘the past and the present and where they are at in their lives’. A place of possibilities In Portals to the Past primary-age children (10–11  years) in Rawmarsh, Rotherham, explored the past by stepping through a portal built from timber by the project’s artist, Steve Pool (Figure 2). The portal acted like a time-machine. As they stepped through the portal, the children chose when and where in the past they wanted to research. Classroom sessions, led by academics from education and English literature, explored aspects of Rawmarsh’s history, including mining heritage through the texts of local author Arthur Eaglestone and Anglo-Saxon writing and culture. These activities were enhanced with a small archaeological excavation alongside play and improvisation outside in which the children devised their own short films to be screened in the classroom (see Pool 2013). The central premise of the project, designed in collaboration with Rotherham Youth Service, was to introduce children to the imaginative possibilities of history. Although academic researchers led the sessions, the facilitators invited the children to draw upon their existing knowledge of history and become researchers themselves. The portal, as described by Steve, was a ‘proposition’, a threshold that marked the boundary between past and present, fact and fiction: the portal grew from the idea that the past wasn’t fixed. The idea of history was kind of under question because we weren’t looking for reality we were looking for the idea of time travelling – you could travel to the future or you could travel to the past. (SP – artist and educator) Although prompted by academics and aided, in part, by classroom resources, the children were free to select their own period from history: it’s critical that they found their own area of enquiry and then researched it themselves and that doesn’t neces- sarily mean that they went in books it could mean that they asked each-other what it could feel like to go down the pit or what it would be like to be in the war or what it would feel like to win the World Cup, so it was a very personally-centred research process. (SP) Figure 2. School children from rawmarsh step through the ‘Portal to the Past’. Source and image copyright: Steve Pool. 8 R. JOHNSTON AND K. MARWOOD Kate Pahl, the academic lead on the project, explained why it was important that the children were co-researchers in the project. It made it possible for the children to appreciate the past as open, as a place of possibilities, as something creative in the present and for the future: the children were finding their own heritage and their own past. What came out was a very imaginative space of practice. Having watched children use the internet in the past it has the effect of closing down the ‘as if ’, the site of possibility. And my interest in the project has always been this idea of the past as almost like a ‘not yet’ future – it’s a real kind of challenge to this concept of what history is. (KP – university researcher) The research emerged as an interesting and evolving process, which countered some of the children’s perceptions of history as immutable: one of the things a child said about the [archaeological] dig was that they never knew what was going to come out of the dig and it’s almost like you never know what was going to happen next and because experts kept appearing there was an on-going surprise element and then they went to the archives at the end. It almost felt like it was making history a different proposition from the proposition of it being a fixed thing, through the doing of it through the week; it was like going through the portal rethought history. (KP) There was an important tension between the imaginative and open spaces that heritage offered and the authenticity of the experience and the agencies of the children. In terms of authenticity, the archaeo- logical excavation is a particularly important example. The project began with the idea of simulating an archaeological excavation in a sand pit. This changed when two trained archaeologists joined the project and suggested they undertook ‘real’ excavations in the school’s grounds. Kate recognised this as significant: the dig began and it was beautiful, the dig, the children absolutely loved it and I was really excited because actually the affordances of the dig as an actual dig suddenly swooped over them because there they were finding clay pipes, they were finding coal, they were finding all of this stuff that was just incredibly generative. (KP) This valuing of authenticity highlights that the experience of researching was transformed by greater equality in the roles that the children took on alongside the ‘experts’ and their access to the resources of knowledge and tools. Kate had doubts about whether the children could undertake the project, and particularly if they had the abilities to make the films. Yet, when challenged, the children responded positively and excitedly to the opportunities. This is one of the challenges of recognition, arguably, that it requires us to change our expectations or our assumptions about people. In recognising where knowledge and skills lie, we open the possibilities for empowerment: I think the week was a kind of playing with their agency being in a new space and it was definitely a different kind of experience, which I think everybody who was involved in that week would say was quite different. The portal idea was part of that difference – it’s the expansion of what you can do. You can go through a portal, you can be different, you can think differently, even with experts coming in. (KP) A social fellowship For our final conversation we visited the Heeley History Workshop, a local history group that meets weekly to discuss memories and stories relating to the parish of Heeley in Sheffield (Figure 3). Their project, Social Life in Heeley and Thereabouts, documented the recreational activities of people in Heeley during the twentieth century. They recovered memories of church life, Boys’ and Girls’ Brigades and street parties using photographs, documents and oral histories. Working with a filmmaker and photographer, the group produced a short film that communicated their findings and portrayed their research processes. The film revealed how shared histories combined with a passion for research cre- ates networks and friendships or what Lilian (LH), the group’s chairperson, refers to in the film as a ‘social fellowship’ (Thorpe 2013). Although some members use the local archives for their research, the participants mainly collect their material from the community, as Lilian described: it’s amazing when you are doing research you’ll find out something that links up with something, either that somebody else knew about or they were interested in and they got the chance to link with somebody else to get some more information and sometimes you can find almost that you are related to each other. (LH) INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HERITAGE STUDIES 9 Lilian explained that participants return to the group for two reasons: ‘because they enjoy the social contact’ and ‘because they are interested in what we are finding and that they might have a link with more of the research that somebody might be doing’. This is a sentiment echoed by Sid who, in addition to attending to share his memories of Heeley, also ‘comes for the company’. The books the group pro- duces are a combination of anecdotes, personal stories and family photographs set alongside archival research conducted by group members in local libraries and archives. The group was motivated by an urge to document or retrieve something from the past that had been neglected or forgotten. They were lamenting the loss of social life in the area, particularly recreational activities that involved the community coming together in times of need or to celebrate Christian festivals. Lilian, for example, spoke about how in the past ‘a lot of people were more content that they are today, it wasn’t a materialistic world’. She described acts of neighbourliness as the ‘sort of thing that people look back to in the good old days’. Not knowing your neighbours and those in your own community can leave you ‘really isolated and lonely even if you are surrounded by people living in houses and that is so sad’. They are forging a new community by coming together to research and learn from each other about their own pasts and the area’s history. This community of researchers became manifest through the participants’ shared connections with Heeley, whether or not they lived in the parish, and most critically through their help for one another (sharing expertise): Some have become more interested in their family history because they have got help from other people. Jean, who has not been here today, she does a lot of work on family history and she’s done quite a lot for Janet whose grandparents and great, great grandparents lived here, she’s also done a lot on David’s family history research because he didn’t know a great deal about it. Sid has done quite a lot, not just on people in this group, but he’s done quite a lot for other people who visited the group and Roger’s done some of his own research and Jean’s done some of it. (LH) Through research they have established what Derek, a member of the group, described as ‘a social gathering’. Although they are different people, they have built a community founded on an interest Figure 3. a meeting of Heeley History Workshop. Source and image copyright: gemma thorpe. 10 R. JOHNSTON AND K. MARWOOD in and an attachment to place and in asking and answering questions about that place. Their social fellowship is both a means of researching heritage and a response to a decline in cooperative social life that the group recognises in present-day Heeley. They are countering a condition that Richard Sennett and others have also observed: ‘modern life is ‘de-skilling’ people in practising cooperation’ (Sennett 2012, 8). The process of co-production (working with academics, filmmakers and students) and experimenting with new methods, such as filmmaking, storytelling and recording oral histories, revealed that although they were seeking to document a time when a sense of community was central to the social life of working people, that process forged a new community or fellowship of researchers (see Wenger 1998). Disrupting misrecognition and maldistribution in heritage projects We began this article with an explanation of heritage as a resource in society that is contingent upon and conditions social action. Heritage is caught up in political and cultural discourses on multiple levels, and influences power relations and identities in the present and into the future. Societies are unequal and unjust to varying degrees and the agencies of heritage management unavoidably work with, perpetuate and have the potential to change these inequalities. It is widely argued that because of this there is a moral imperative to appreciate and address inequalities in access, participation and representation of marginalised groups within society during heritage practice (e.g. Byrne 2008; Newman and McLean 1998; Sandell and Nightingale 2013). While this principle might be relatively uncontentious, there is considerably more variation in and dispute about the best ways to democratise heritage, make it widely accessible and relevant, and part of a process for positive social change. We are particularly interested in the application of Nancy Fraser’s theorisation of social justice, in which she makes the case for accommodating both recognition and redistribution. Fraser’s work has received limited attention in heritage studies, although Laurajane Smith and Emma Waterton have employed it effectively to explain how parity of participation can foster ‘a heritage practice that identifies subordinate status within the management process and reconstitutes those groups so that they find an equitable position from which to interact fully, as peers’ (Smith and Waterton 2009, 81). Our approach is distinctive because we have sought to understand the ways that researching her- itage, as a practice, can plainly and self-consciously work towards social justice within and poten- tially beyond projects. We accept that our concern with community-based research aligns with Participatory Action Research (PAR) (Prasad 2014) and related community-based research models that are increasingly employed in archaeology, public history and museums (see chapters in Atalay et al. 2014; Facer and Enright 2016, 82–89). However, we would make a distinction between the prioritisation of achieving wider social change in PAR and the more diverse priorities within the community projects in which we were involved: for instance, documenting social life in Heeley and studying the archives and architectural history of a Georgian building. A second distinction to make is between the rather narrow disciplinary approaches that characterise public or community archaeology and public history when compared with the mélange of activity (as academics we might term it interdisciplinarity – though see below for an alternative term) that constitutes research within community heritage projects. We used three case studies from RCH to explore the influence of researching within heritage projects. The case studies offer a method for expanding and enriching our initial observation about the role that research might be playing within the projects. They served a heuristic process through which we devised a framework for undertaking future projects. We term this framework action herit- age and describe it in the following section. A key influence on the formation of this framework were ‘disruptions’ within each of the case studies. By disruption, we mean perceptible changes that took place in how the projects were oriented and how the participants (including ourselves) thought about the research. We think these disruptions reveal material and social inequalities within the projects. These disruptions share some characteristics and in other respects are specific to individual projects. INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HERITAGE STUDIES 11 We will take a moment to review these disruptions and to relate them to the concepts of recognition and redistribution that are core to Fraser’s theory of social justice. Working with the young people staying at the Roundabout hostel, the disruption in the research process occurred when the residents began incorporating their personal stories into the scrapbook that the project used to document the research. The scrapbook emerged as a disruption during the conversation with the project team and in our reflections about the scrapbook workshop. The session and the scrapbook, as artefact, provoked greater participation and engagement from residents com- pared with the other activities. This represented a shift in the recognition of the residents and their stake in the project. We suggest there were two dependent actions that made recognition effective. The first was the emphasis in the scrapbook on personal histories rather than the building’s story, which made the research more directly relevant to the participants and made their contributions more direct and accessible. This was itself dependent upon a recognition of the residents’ stories as valid research within the project. The scrapbook also enabled a redistribution of a resource – the hostel’s archive – from Roundabout to the residents. Ray, the youth worker, commented on the way the scrapbook differed from the residents’ digital files held at the hostel by being ‘tangible’ and something the res- idents produced themselves. In discussing the experiences of care-leavers in Australia, Wilson and Golding (2016) proposed that the children should have greater participation in the creation of the official records of their time in state care. The scrapbook at Roundabout perhaps offers an example of how participation in the creation of archives might be enacted. This disruption illustrates how a shift in the project’s objectives (away from the building and towards the personal histories of the residents) increased parity in the roles and status of the participants within the project and changed the character of engagement. It was a relatively unproblematic refocusing in the Roundabout project because the outcomes of the archival researches were thin and the ‘standard’ research activities (e.g. library visits) were less successful in attracting interest from the young people. In Portals to the Past, the underlying idea of the project was disruptive in that it offered children an opportunity to be creative and imaginative with history: ‘we weren’t looking for reality’ (SP). The disruption, in the terms that we are using here and which came out most clearly in our discussion with the project team, was in certain respects the least creative part of the project: the archaeological excavation. It showed that even when there are strong principles of social justice and co-production at the core of a project, as there was in Portals to the Past, misrecognition and maldistribution can still exist within components or activities. The excavation was initially planned as a simulation, where the children excavated objects hidden within a sand pit. Yet the archaeologists decided to open real excavations in the school grounds. This changed the dynamic for all the participants, both the children and the academic researchers. The shift from simulated to real excavation marked a recognition of the children’s abilities to participate successfully in the research. We would also interpret it as a form of redistribution, because the children were given access to the archaeologists’ tools and taught to use them: trowels, sieves and trays for artefacts. The excavation was successful because it yoked these aspects together: recognition of the children’s capabilities to excavate, and redistributing the resources that make excavation possible alongside professional archaeologists. The real excavation did not remove distinctions between the adult professionals and the young researchers, but it did acknowledge where the inequalities lay and sought to ameliorate them. The Heeley History Workshop offered the least potential for disruption as the group is well-estab- lished and has spent many years researching Heeley and publishing books about its history. Much of the project’s expertise lay within the group, while the university brought academic researchers, students to help with digital recording, and a filmmaker. It was Gemma Thorpe’s film about the project that became the disruption (Thorpe 2013). Rather than documenting the outcomes of the group’s research – recreational activities in Heeley – she instead collected images and audio recordings of the group talking about the process of doing the research and reflecting on the character of the group itself. We remember feeling apprehensive when the film was shown for the first time, at a gathering to celebrate the end of the project. Yet the film was well-regarded and it stimulated a continuing discussion, which we took into our recorded conversation with the group, about the character of the social fellowship that 12 R. JOHNSTON AND K. MARWOOD emerges through participation in the research. We perceive this as an example of how recognition and redistribution works within a community organisation through research: recognising one another’s contributions and sharing knowledge and learning. This is not a smooth, unproblematic process. It brings out tensions between individuals, asymmetries in status and so forth. The point, though, is that the group perceives the fellowship as the normative state and one that is largely a consequence of the group’s purpose: researching Heeley’s heritage. These three disruptions are examples of how acts of recognition and redistribution can influence the parity of participation within heritage research projects. The case studies also illustrate the ways that researching is socially active and empowering: it personally connects the participants with the heritage that forms the focus of the projects (at Roundabout, the young people’s stories in the scrapbook became more important than the story of the hostel); researching opened up new (future) versions of the past for the children in Rotherham, and critically it was a heritage they controlled and created; and the local history group in Heeley found connections with one another, making and remaking their community in the present through their research into Heeley’s past. These reaffirm for us that the practices and processes of researching heritage are transformative and create diverse social and cultural capital (see Graham 2002). Action heritage We conclude by generalising from our analysis of the RCH projects to present a framework for co- produced heritage research, which we term action heritage. Action heritage privileges process (action) over outcomes and addresses social inequalities through a dispersed and redistributive model of research practice. We identify four vectors to the action heritage framework: undisciplinary research, active rather than activist, with parity of participation, which is sustainable and sustained (Figure 4). Figure 4. the action heritage framework. INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HERITAGE STUDIES 13 Researching community heritage should be undisciplinary. As academic researchers within RCH, we were a multidisciplinary team comprising archaeologists, ethnographers, historians, linguists, literature specialists and musicologists. The project brought us to interdisciplinary spaces and into profitable collaborations with one another. Contrastingly, the community-based researchers under- stood but did not affiliate with the disciplinary differences we recognised as academics and which contributed to our identities during the project. They approached research questions and evidence without any prior disciplinary claims or boundaries. They were undisciplinary (‘indisciplinaire’), to use a category within the taxonomy that Ayuko Sedooka and colleagues recently published (2015, 375, 376). We would suggest that the term ‘heritage’ has a powerful role in recognising the validity of this undisciplinary position and enabling the variety of activity that constitutes research within community heritage projects. The second vector of our framework is the privileging of process over outcomes, which is to say emphasising the transformative experiences of researching over the impacts achieved from research results. This has been a prominent strand throughout this article, as we have sought to understand the ways that researching heritage, as a practice, can plainly and self-consciously work in more socially just ways. We accept that our framework aligns with PAR and related community-based research models. These models are founded on a commitment to working with members of communities that have traditionally been exploited or oppressed in efforts to bring about social change (Kindon, Pain, and Kesby 2007). They foreground the research process as a means of enabling social action: ‘gener- ating knowledge that is both valid and vital to the well-being of individuals, communities, and for the promotion of larger-scale democratic social change’ (Brydon-Miller, Greenwood, and Maguire 2003, 11). However, we would make a distinction between the prioritisation of achieving social change in PAR and the more diverse interests and priorities within the community projects in which we were involved. In the case of RCH, where the projects were funded for a maximum of 12 months, it would be unrealistic to judge the success of projects on whether they achieved wider, large-scale social change. Such ambitions take time. However, we could undertake research about heritage that ‘challenges unjust and undemocratic economic, social and political systems and practices’ (Brydon-Miller, Greenwood, and Maguire 2003, 11) within the research process. The third vector of our framework is the application of a dispersed and redistributive model of research practice. This model aspires to parity of participation in research by explicitly drawing on Nancy Fraser’s theories about recognition, redistribution and social justice. Social justice is achieved by enabling full participation through equality of status and access to resources. In the context of heritage research, this means surfacing and addressing inequalities between community-based and institutionally-based participants. This must involve recognising the expertise that lies within com- munities and ensuring that the resources for research are fairly distributed to enable more equal opportunities to participate. There are cases of universities and funders that, in parts or whole, accept and support these principles. There are many more examples where structures and policies perpet- uate inequalities through misrecognition and maldistribution. Coming from a university, our sense is that this is a challenge to universities and funding bodies to take responsibility for breaking down inequalities in who has opportunities to participate in research. Universities can achieve this in many tangible ways: for instance, by opening access to their research tools (such as libraries and archives) for community-based researchers, and bringing community-based expertise into research governance (Beebeejaun et al. 2015). Universities are amongst the institutions that should take responsibility for the fourth vector of action heritage: sustainable and sustained. The durations of the RCH projects we reviewed in this article were limited by funding and the consequent availability of staff in the partner organisations and the university. This made it difficult for us to achieve long-term legacies, although anecdotally we know there have been some (see Vergunst et al. 2017, 162–165). In the Roundabout project, for instance, the one participant who attended all the research sessions was also the person who the youth worker identified as most changed by the experience. Ours is not an isolated experience (e.g. Atalay 2012, 128–166). In their review of the Connected Communities programme, Facer and Enright (2016, 14 R. JOHNSTON AND K. MARWOOD 158) recommended to universities and funders that time is considered as ‘critical infrastructure’ for collaborative research: ‘time is to collaborative research what a supercomputer is to big data’. We have incorporated time into action heritage as our foundational vector: sustainable and sustained collaborations. We will finish by returning to the school in Rawmarsh that opened our article. Reflecting on the project, Kate Pahl said, ‘I do think there is something about the way [the children] did become experts and it did reposition them. I mean, I particularly remember this one kid talking about the miner’s strike and finding out how much he was earning and he said, “that’s shocking!”’. It is this repositioning of the participants as researchers that we believe was so powerful within RCH. Action heritage is our attempt to distill this repositioning into a framework that can be applied widely and purposefully to achieve social justice through sustained participation in research. Acknowledgements Research for Community Heritage comprised a wide network of researchers in both academic and community settings. For their contributions to the projects we discussed in this article, we would like to thank Ben Keegan and Ray Anderson of Roundabout, Trudie White, Justine Gaubert, Heeley History Workshop (particularly Lillian Haywood), Stephanie Liantzakis, Lousia Stokoe, Caroline Weston, Sarah Hollingdale, Gemma Thorpe, Karen Harvey, David Forrest, Kate Pahl, Steve Pool, Marcus Hurcombe, Hugh Escott, Christine Wallis, Rebecca Hearne and Sara Farey. The university-based researchers on our project were funded by the Arts and Humanities Research Council’s Connected Communities Programme (grants AH/J013498/1 and AH/K007769/1). The community-based researchers were supported by the Heritage Lottery Fund. We are also grateful for additional support from the University of Sheffield’s Arts Enterprise initi- ative. We have enjoyed and profited from opportunities to discuss our ideas with colleagues at a Connected Communities symposium on co-production and social justice organised by Keri Facer, Andrew Miles, Pat Thomson and Tom Wakeford, and research seminars in Aberdeen, Dublin and Durham. We also learnt a lot from colleagues and collaborators who read and gave us feedback on earlier drafts of this article: David Forrest, Helen Graham, Karen Harvey, Dawn Hadley, Jane Hodson, Jeff Oliver, Kate Pahl, Toby Pillatt, Jo Vergunst and this journal’s anonymous reviewers. Disclosure statement No potential conflict of interest was reported by the authors. Funding This work was supported by Arts and Humanities Research Council [grant number AH/J013498/1, grant number AH/ K007769/1]. Notes on contributors Robert Johnston is a Senior Lecturer in Landscape Archaeology in the Department of Archaeology, University of Sheffield. He researches and teaches in the fields of cultural landscapes, community heritage and later prehistoric archaeology. Kimberley Marwood is a Project Officer working on civic engagement and public value in the Projects and Development Team in Academic and Learning Services at the University of Sheffield. She researches art history and heritage using participatory research methods, including action research and co-production. References Ander, Erica, Linda Thomson, Guy Noble, Anne Lanceley, Usha Menon, and Helen Chatterjee. 2013. “Heritage, Health and Well-being: Assessing the Impact of a Heritage Focused Intervention on Health and Well-being.” International Journal of Heritage Studies 19 (3): 229–242. doi:10.1080/13527258.2011.651740. Atalay, Sonya. 2012. Community-based Archeology: Research with, by and for Indigenous and Local Communities. Berkeley: University of California Press. Atalay, Sonya, Lee Rains Claus, Randall H. McGuire, and John R. Welch, eds. 2014. Transforming Archaeology: Activist Practices and Prospects. Walnut Creek, CA: Left Coast Press. https://doi.org/10.1080/13527258.2011.651740 INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF HERITAGE STUDIES 15 Beebeejaun, Yasminah, Catherine Durose, James Rees, Jo Richardson, and Liz Richardson. 2015. “Public Value or Public Harm? Towards Co-production in Research with Communities.” Environment and Planning C 33 (3): 552–565. doi:10.1068/c12116. Brydon-Miller, Mary, Davydd Greenwood, and Patricia Maguire. 2003. “Why Action Research?” Action Research 1 (1): 9–28. doi:10.1177/14767503030011002. Byrne, Denis. 2008. “Heritage as Social Action.” In The Heritage Reader, edited by Graham Fairclough, Rodney Harrison, John Schofield and John H. Jameson Jr, 209–218. London: Routledge. Facer, Keri, and Bryony Enright. 2016. Creating Living Knowledge: The Connected Communities Programme, Community University Relationships and the Participatory Turn in the Production of Knowledge. Bristol: University of Bristol/ AHRC Connected Communities. Fraser, Nancy. 2000. “Rethinking Recognition.” New Left Review 3 (May–June): 107–120. Fraser, Nancy. 2003. “Social Justice in the Age of Identity Politics.” In Redistribution or Recognition? A Political- philosophical Exchange, edited by Nancy Fraser and Axel Honneth, 7–109. London: Verso. Freire, Paulo. 2002. Education for Critical Consciousness. New York: Continuum. Graham, Brian. 2002. “Heritage as Knowledge: Capital or Culture?” Urban Studies 39 (5–6): 1003–1017. doi:10.1080/00420980220128426. Graham, Brian, Greg Ashworth, and John Tunbridge. 2016. A Geography of Heritage: Power, Culture and Economy. London: Routledge. Harrison, Rodney. 2010. “Heritage as Social Action.” In Understanding Heritage in Practice, edited by Susie West, 240–276. Manchester, NH: Manchester University Press. Harrison, Rodney. 2013. Heritage: Critical Approaches. London: Routledge. Harvey, David C. 2001. “Heritage Pasts and Heritage Presents: Temporality, Meaning and the Scope of Heritage Studies.” International Journal of Heritage Studies. 7 (4): 319–338. doi:10.1080/13581650120105534. Heritage Decisions Research Team. 2015. How Should Heritage Decisions Be Made? Increasing Participation from Where You Are. http://pvac-sites.leeds.ac.uk/ccsmgh/files/2015/06/HD-book-final-A4-pages1.pdf. Kiddey, Rachael. 2017. “From the Ground up: Cultural Heritage Practices as Tools for Empowerment in the Homeless Heritage Project.” International Journal of Heritage Studies. Advance Online Publication. doi:10.1080/13527258.20 16.1274669. Kindon, Sara, Rachel Pain, and Mike Kesby. 2007. “Participatory Action Research: Origins, Approaches and Methods.” In Participatory Action Research Approaches and Methods: Connecting People, Participation and Place, edited by Sara Kindon, Rachel Pain and Mike Kesby, 9–18. London: Routledge. Krueger, Richard A., and Mary Anne Casey. 2009. Focus Groups: A Practical Guide for Applied Research. London: Sage. Lister, Ruth. 2008. “Recognition and Voice: The Challenge for Social Justice.” In Social Justice and Public Policy: Seeking Fairness in Diverse Societies, edited by Gary Craig, Tania Burchardt and David Gordon, 105–122. Bristol: The Policy Press. McGhee, Fred L. 2012. “Participatory Action Research and Archaeology.” In The Oxford Handbook of Public Archaeology, edited by Robin Skeates, Carol McDavid and John Carman, 213–229. Oxford: Oxford University Press. McGuire, Randall H. 2008. Archaeology as Political Action. Berkeley: University of California Press. Newman, Andrew, and Fiona McLean. 1998. “Heritage Builds Communities: The Application of Heritage Resources to the Problems of Social Exclusion.” International Journal of Heritage Studies 4 (3–4): 143–153. doi:10.1080/13527259808722232. Ostrom, Elinor. 1996. “Crossing the Great Divide: Coproduction, Synergy, and Development.” World Development 24 (6): 1073–1087. doi:10.1016/0305-750X(96)00023-X. Pahl, Kate, and Steve Pool. 2011. “Living Your Life Because It’s the Only Life You’ve Got.” Qualitative Research Journal 11 (2): 17–37. doi:10.3316/QRJ1102017. Pool, Steve. 2013. Portals to the past. http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=IWC41_D_w9o. Prasad, B. Devi. 2014. “Social Justice.” In The SAGE Encyclopedia of Action Research, edited by David Coghlan and Mary Brydon-Miller, 708–711. London: Sage. Sandell, Richard, and Eithne Nightingale, eds. 2013. Museums, Equality and Social Justice. London: Routledge. Sedooka, Ayuko, Gabriela Steffen, Theres Paulsen, and Frédéric Darbellay. 2015. “Paradoxe identitaire et interdisciplinarité: un regard sur les identités disciplinaires des chercheurs.” [The Paradox of Identity and Interdisciplinarity: A Study of the Disciplinary Identities of Researchers.] Natures Sciences Sociétés 23: 367–377. doi:10.1051/nss/2015056. Sennett, Richard. 2012. Together: The Rituals, Pleasures and Politics of Cooperation. London: Allen Lane. Smith, Laurajane. 2006. The Uses of Heritage. Abingdon: Routledge. Smith, Laurajane, and Emma Waterton. 2009. Heritage, Communities and Archaeology. London: Duckworth. Smith, Laurajane, Paul Shackel, and Gary Campbell. 2011. “Introduction: Class Still Matters.” In Heritage, Labour and the Working Classes, edited by Laurajane Smith, Paul Shackel and Gary Campbell, 1–16. Abingdon: Routledge. Thorpe, Gemma. 2013. Living Heritage. http://vimeo.com/68523096. Vergunst, Jo, Elizabeth Curtis, Oliver Davis, Helen Graham, Robert Johnston, and Colin Shepherd. 2017. “Material Legacies: Shaping Things and Places through Heritage.” In Valuing Interdisciplinary Collaborative Research: Beyond Impact, edited by Keri Facer and Kate Pahl, 153–171. Bristol: Policy Press. https://doi.org/10.1068/c12116 https://doi.org/10.1177/14767503030011002 https://doi.org/10.1080/00420980220128426 https://doi.org/10.1080/13581650120105534 http://pvac-sites.leeds.ac.uk/ccsmgh/files/2015/06/HD-book-final-A4-pages1.pdf https://doi.org/10.1080/13527258.2016.1274669 https://doi.org/10.1080/13527258.2016.1274669 https://doi.org/10.1080/13527259808722232 https://doi.org/10.1016/0305-750X(96)00023-X https://doi.org/10.3316/QRJ1102017 http://www.youtube.com/watch?v=IWC41_D_w9o https://doi.org/10.1051/nss/2015056 http://vimeo.com/68523096 16 R. JOHNSTON AND K. MARWOOD Waterton, Emma, and Laurajane Smith. 2010. “The Recognition and Misrecognition of Community Heritage.” International Journal of Heritage Studies 16 (1–2): 4–15. doi:10.1080/13527250903441671. Wenger, Etienne. 1998. Communities of Practice: Learning, Meaning, and Identity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Wilson, Jacqueline Z., and Frank Golding. 2016. “Latent Scrutiny: Personal Archives as Perpetual Mementos of the Official Gaze.” Archival Science 16 (1): 93–109. doi:10.1007/s10502-015-9255-3. https://doi.org/10.1080/13527250903441671 https://doi.org/10.1007/s10502-015-9255-3 Abstract Introduction Heritage as action, as socially active research Better than doing nothing A place of possibilities A social fellowship Disrupting misrecognition and maldistribution in heritage projects Action heritage Acknowledgements Disclosure statement Funding Notes on contributors References work_bv2jgdm2rbhshlxyuqygifxe3i ---- Kelleher_BJHC_FINAL_accurate biblio 1 Beneficence, Justice, and Health Care1 J. Paul Kelleher Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 24(1) (March 2014) [Author’s note: The journal sent a pre-copy-edited version of this paper to the publisher, who then published it. The publisher blames the journal, and the journal refuses to pay the publisher’s fee to correct the mistakes. The copy before you now is the copy-edited version that (among other things) fixes some bibliographical inaccuracies.] ABSTRACT. This paper argues that societal duties of health promotion are underwritten (at least in large part) by a principle of beneficence. Further, this principle generates duties of justice that correlate with rights, not merely “imperfect” duties of charity or generosity. To support this argument, I draw on a useful distinction from bioethics and on a somewhat neglected approach to social obligation from political philosophy. The distinction is that between general and specific beneficence; and the approach from political philosophy has at times been called equality of concern. After clarifying the distinction and setting out the basis of the equality of concern view, I argue that the result is a justice-based principle of “specific” beneficence that should be reflected in a society’s health policy. I then draw on this account to criticize, refine, and extend some prominent health care policy proposals from the bioethics literature. Must societies actively promote their members’ health, rather than merely protecting them against the health-harming acts of others? This question can be broken down into two parts. The first part asks why health is important to individuals. Two leading answers are that health is important because of how it bears on individuals’ well-being (Broome 2002) and because of how it bears on their effective opportunities (i.e. what they can effectively do and be in life) (Sen 1980; Daniels 1981). I will assume that at least one of these views is correct, and in this paper I seek to address the second part of the opening question. The second part asks what (if any) 1 For comments and discussion on material included here, I would like to thank Dan Hausman, Gordon Hull, Win-chiat Lee, John C. Moskop, and participants at the 2013 Junior Scholars in Bioethics Workshop at Wake Forest University. 2 normative principles account for a society’s responsibilities to promote the health of its members, and what shape do those responsibilities take? Many bioethicists and political philosophers believe that it must be a principle of justice that provides the key link between the importance of health to individuals and the health- promoting responsibilities of society. But not everyone agrees. As Allen Buchanan has written, “The difficulty is that we may be much surer that someone ought not to lack a certain form of health care than we are about whether the ground of this judgment is a principle that structures our sense of justice or our sense of charity or beneficence or generosity” (1984, p. 57). And after struggling to find a sound principle of justice that guarantees a decent minimum of health care to all, Buchanan famously concludes that a decent minimum should be provided as a matter of law, but that the normative basis for this draws most heavily upon considerations of harm-prevention and prudence, and upon principles of enforceable beneficence and charity, rather than principles of justice. Buchanan concedes that individuals do not in general possess a moral right that their society actively promote their health, because individuals do not possess rights to beneficence. However, Buchanan insists that this is not cause for dismay, since it nicely explains why we find it so difficult to be precise about what a decent minimum should include. For in his view (and indeed in the view of many theorists), duties of beneficence are “imperfect” duties, which “by their very nature . . . are not precisely delineated” (p. 77) and which tolerate considerable leeway in deciding how and when to discharge them. In this paper I too will defend the view that societal duties of health promotion are underwritten (at least in large part) by a principle of beneficence. But I will argue that this principle is a principle of justice, and that the duties it generates correlate with rights. In support of this argument, I will draw on a useful distinction from bioethics and on a somewhat neglected 3 approach to social obligation from political philosophy. The distinction is that between general and specific beneficence; and the approach from political philosophy has at times been called equality of concern. After clarifying the distinction (section 1) and exploring the basis of the equality of concern view (sections 2 and 3), I argue that the result is a justice-based principle of “specific” beneficence that should be reflected in a society’s health-related public policy. In section 4 I discuss ways in which this view should shape health policy. Despite endorsing some concrete conclusions, my discussion in this final section is admittedly vague. But as I shall argue, Buchanan was incorrect to associate vagueness with charity and precision with justice. When it comes to justice in health care, sometimes vague principles are all that moral theory has to offer. Section 5 concludes. 1. GENERAL AND SPECIFIC BENEFICENCE I will understand beneficence as action that promotes another’s interests for its own sake, and not merely because another’s doing well is instrumentally useful for one’s own purposes. It is important to distinguish this conceptual understanding of beneficence from two further moral claims. The first is the claim that there is some duty (or duties) to be beneficent. This is a claim I shall argue for. The second moral claim is that duties of beneficence (if they exist) are always duties of generosity or charity, and never duties of justice. This is a claim I reject. Beauchamp and Childress draw a further distinction between general and specific beneficence. They write that specific beneficence “is directed at particular parties, such as children, friends, contractors, or patients. . . . By contrast, general beneficence is directed beyond special relationships to all persons” (2013, p. 205). This distinction is not uncontroversial. For instance, while Beauchamp and Childress draw heavily upon the moral framework of W. D. 4 Ross, some of Ross’s remarks suggest that he would bridle at the notion of “specific” beneficence. Ross claims that duties of beneficence are those that “rest on the mere fact that there are other beings in the world whose condition we can make better in respect of virtue, or of intelligence, or of pleasure” (1930, p. 21). This formulation clearly betokens Beauchamp’s and Childress’s notion of general beneficence. Ross further suggests that beneficence should be distinguished from moral requirements that derive from special relationships. He writes: In fact the theory of “ideal utilitarianism” . . . seems to simplify unduly our relations to our fellows. It says, in effect, that the only morally significant relation in which my neighbours stand to me is that of being possible beneficiaries by my action. They do stand in this relation to me, and this relation is morally significant. But they may also stand to me in the relation of promisee to promiser, of creditor to debtor, of wife to husband, of child to parent, of friend to friend, of fellow countryman to fellow countryman, and the like; and each of these relations is the foundation of a prima facie duty, which is more or less incumbent on me according to the circumstances of the case. (p. 19) When combined with Ross’s understanding of beneficence, this passage in effect claims that there is more to morality than beneficence, and that this further content relates to our past actions and our special relationships. This gives some support to the view that “specific” beneficence is a misnomer: for Ross, it seems as if beneficence is always general beneficence whose rationale rests on “the mere fact that there are other beings in the world whose condition we can make better.” Whatever might be called “specific beneficence” should, Ross suggests, be called something else. In Bioethics: A Systematic Approach, Gert, Culver, and Clouser (GCC) also reject the notion of specific beneficence. In response to Beauchamp and Childress, GCC write [Beauchamp and Childress] are clear that doctors, nurses, and others in the health care field have specific duties to their patients that are determined by their profession and by the practices of their specific institution. To lump these varied and detailed professional duties together with the misconceived “general duty of beneficence” and place them all under one principle of beneficence is to substitute a slogan for substance. (Gert, Culver, and Clouser 2006, p. 120) 5 GCC here press two objections to Beauchamp and Childress’s discussion of beneficence. First, GCC do not agree that general beneficence is a genuine moral obligation. In their view, it is better categorized as a moral ideal, which grants persons the “choice in deciding when to follow [it] and with regard to whom” (p. 115). Second, GCC hold that when there is a genuine duty to promote another’s interests, that duty will come from some more specific relationship (e.g. the doctor/patient relationship), and it should therefore not be classified as a form of beneficence at all. Thus in one respect GCC are closer to Ross than are Beauchamp and Childress, and in another respect GCC are farther from him. GCC are closer to Ross insofar as they distinguish sharply between the morality of beneficence and the morality of special relationships; but they are farther from Ross insofar as GCC refuse to speak of duties or obligations of beneficence at all. Since I intend to endorse justice-based duties of specific beneficence that have their basis in special relationships, I must reject the view, explicit in GCC and implicit in Ross, that the only genuine form of beneficence is general beneficence. To begin making my case, I note first that others in the Rossian tradition are quite willing to speak of duties of beneficence that arise out of special relationships. For example, the leading intuitionist philosopher in the Rossian tradition, Robert Audi, writes I begin by speculating with a notion of autonomy that might be considered broadly Kantian . . . , but also might be viewed as Rossian insofar as it takes duties to others to arise in specific relationships. . . . On the radical autonomy view, we do not have a duty of beneficence unless we autonomously incur it. We often do incur it, of course, and in at least two ways: explicitly, say by promising to do good deeds, and implicitly, by some other free undertaking or commitment. (2004 p. 95) For Audi, then, the notion of specific beneficence is not conceptually incoherent, since it is not incoherent to speak of a duty of beneficence arising out of a specific deed or relationship. Still, 6 even if Audi is correct that the notion is not incoherent, it is clearly a separate question whether it is theoretically useful to speak in terms of specific beneficence. In my view, there are indeed good theoretical reasons to retain and employ the concept of specific beneficence. For one thing, many special duties appear to require the cultivation and exercise of a disposition to promote another’s interests or good. Since “beneficence” is already a perfectly good term to characterize action of that sort, I see no reason to avoid it simply because the relevant duty has its basis in a special relationship. Second, we can easily give further texture to the distinction between duties of general beneficence and duties of specific beneficence by saying that only the latter correlate with claims. A child, for example, has a claim on the beneficence of her parent. By contrast, while it may be true that I would have genuine moral reasons to display beneficence toward each of a billion intelligent creatures discovered on Venus, GCC are arguably correct that none of them can invoke a corresponding claim against me.2 (This conclusion might not follow in certain well-defined cases of nearby rescue, but I lack the space to explore that possibility here.3) Thus, we can say that general beneficence is the beneficence I do or should display toward those who nevertheless do not have a claim to it, whereas specific beneficence is beneficence I do or should display toward those who do hold a claim to it. Moreover, once the idea of claims to beneficence is introduced, it is natural to allow that different special relationships generate claims of different strengths. For example: other things equal, a friend’s claim on my beneficence is arguably weaker than my child’s. If, as I believe, these conceptual distinctions are useful and plausible, they can be used to respond to GCC’s claim that “[t]o lump these varied and detailed professional duties together with the misconceived ‘general duty of beneficence’ and place them all under one principle of 2 The Venus example is Thomas Pogge’s (1999). 3 Beauchamp and Childress 2013 discusses rescue cases in more detail (see pp. 206–209). 7 beneficence is to substitute a slogan for substance.” GCC may be right that there is no “one principle of beneficence” that stands above a duty of general beneficence and duties of specific beneficence. But there does not need to be such a “master” principle of beneficence in order for there to be discrete and more narrowly tailored principles of beneficence. One of these can be a general principle of beneficence (which generates either an ideal or a duty), while others can be more specific, having their basis in special relationships. Of course, not all duties stemming from special relationships will be duties of beneficence. Some, for instance, will simply be duties of fidelity that stem from a promise to do this or that quite specific action. But other duties stemming from special relationships are clearly duties that impose less discriminating demands, demands that require one first to assess what is in another’s interests and then to pursue a course of action that substantially promotes those interests. The demands of parenthood are again a good example here. In these latter cases, I see no conceptual or theoretical impediment to calling these duties what they appear to be: duties of beneficence aimed at specific individuals. 2. SPECIFIC BENEFICENCE AND EQUALITY OF CONCERN I have defended Beauchamp and Childress’s distinction between general and specific beneficence, and I suggested that different duties of specific beneficence have their basis in different special relationships and correlate with claims of differing strengths. (I will say more about what it means in practice to have a claim to beneficence in section 4.) With these concepts and distinctions in hand, we can describe Buchanan’s position on rights to health care in slightly different terms from those he used. In Buchanan’s terms, his approach to justifying a legal right to a decent minimum of health care was pluralistic: it sought to combine (1) “arguments from special (as opposed to universal) rights to health care,” (2) arguments about harm-prevention and 8 prudence, and (3) arguments for enforceable general beneficence (Buchanan 1984, p. 66). I want now to argue that the first set of arguments—arguments from so-called “special rights”—suggest that justice generates at least some duties of specific beneficence. Buchanan gives three examples of what he has in mind when he speaks of “special” rights to health care. First is the right that certain individuals posses by virtue of being disadvantaged by historical injustices. Second is the right acquired when one has sustained unjust harm from specific third-parties, such as pollution harms inflicted by corporations. Third and finally, a strong moral case can be made for special rights to health care for those who have undergone exceptional sacrifices for the good of society as a whole—in particular those whose health has been adversely affected through military service. The most obvious candidates for such compensatory special rights are soldiers wounded in combat. (p. 67) Note here that Buchanan seems to accord special rights only to those soldiers “whose health has been adversely affected through military service.” In response it might be asked: why is special concern for soldiers not warranted by the mere fact that they stand ready to risk life and limb for the good of society? It strikes me that the commitment a solider makes to society does in fact warrant a broader concern for her than Buchanan admits. Accordingly, I believe we should say that the special relationship binding society and soldier grounds a social duty of specific beneficence toward the soldier.4 Moreover, soldiers can assert claims on the beneficence of the society they stand ready to defend. If that is right, then we should expand Buchanan’s pluralistic view so that it can also lean on enforceable duties of specific beneficence that correlate with claims. 4 Note, however, that the precise action required by duties of specific beneficence will depend partly upon background institutions and established expectations. As Dan Hausman has suggested to me, if there were a social norm that soldiers’ families were to use the soldiers’ combat pay to address injuries, then a demand for further public assistance may be unjustified. But such a social norm will itself be justified only if combat pay is set from the beginning at a level high enough to reflect the specific beneficence that society owes to the soldier. 9 Buchanan does not say explicitly whether he thinks a soldier’s special right to health care is a right grounded in justice. But his discussion points in that direction, for he strongly distinguishes between special rights and beneficence, and it is only the latter that he associates with charity and generosity (rather than justice). What, then, shall we say about the less discriminating duty of specific beneficence I have claimed is owed to all soldiers (and not just those who are wounded in combat)? Is it a duty of justice? This of course turns on what justice is, and that is a hard and contentious question. Nevertheless, many theorists accept John Stuart Mill’s view that “Justice implies something which it is not only right to do, and wrong not to do, but which some individual person can claim from us as his moral right” (Mill [1861] 2006, p. 102 [chap. 5, para. 15]). If, therefore, a non-battled-tested soldier does in fact possess a claim on society’s beneficence, then the corresponding social duty is arguably one of justice. To be fair, Mill does say in his very next sentence that “No one has a moral right to our generosity or beneficence, because we are not morally bound to practise those virtues toward any given individual.” But by “beneficence” Mill here means “general beneficence,” and thus even if he is correct it does not follow that there are no rights to what we are now calling specific beneficence. Suppose we agree that each soldier has a justice-based claim to the specific beneficence of his or her larger society or political community. Might there be a further case for concluding that each member of society, whether a solider or not, has a similar claim? Buchanan apparently thought not, citing the “exceptional sacrifice” that only people like soldiers make. This skepticism about “scaling up” specific beneficence is, I suspect, shared by many other bioethicists and political philosophers who prefer to ground enforceable, society-wide obligations in quite different principles of distributive justice. There is, however, one line of argument from contemporary political philosophy that argues for such a scaling-up, and it is one 10 that I find attractive. This line of argument has not, however, been articulated in terms of obligatory specific beneficence toward others. Rather, it has been put in terms of a political community’s obligations of equal concern for members of society. A view along these lines has been separately defended by political philosophers Ronald Dworkin (in his later work) and Richard W. Miller. According to Dworkin, “[e]qual concern is the sovereign virtue of political community,” for “[n]o government is legitimate that does not show equal concern for the fate of all those citizens over whom it claims dominion and from whom it claims allegiance” (2002, p. 1). Similarly, Miller claims that “Equal concern is the more appropriate standard [of social justice] because it better reflects the moral significance of democratic citizenship. For equal concern . . . expresses the proper valuing of the institutional loyalties on which a well-ordered democracy depends” (2002, p. 298). I will examine the arguments underlying these claims in more detail in the next section. But before I do so, I want to establish the tight conceptual connection between what Dworkin and Miller refer to as concern for others and what I have been calling specific beneficence. Miller makes this connection plain when he explains that the duties of concern he is arguing for are duties to show “special loyalty to [fellow citizens], displayed in special concern for their needs” (2010, p. 43; emphasis added). For Dworkin’s part, things are complicated by the fact that in his early writings, Dworkin often used the phrase “equal concern and respect” to refer to a highly abstract moral standard that virtually all political theorists, including libertarians, expect a just society to meet (see, e.g., Dworkin 1978, p. 180). But in later writings, Dworkin was clear that by equal concern, he no longer intends the abstract and largely formal notions of equal moral status or equal protection under the laws, but rather a more robust moral standard requiring the promotion of individuals’ substantive interests. For example, he writes: 11 Imagine that a family is about to buy a new house and wishes to buy the house with the largest aggregate bedroom space, measured in overall square feet, that it can afford. Does it show equal concern for its members if it buys the house with the largest average bedroom size even though one bedroom, which it knows will be occupied by the youngest child, is miserable dark and insufferably small? (2008, p. 102) Dworkin’s answer to this rhetorical question is clearly “no,” and he suggests that this way of thinking connects up with the proper way to think about social justice. For he asks, “Given the complex and dramatic impact of a political settlement [i.e. a given socio-economic institutional arrangement] on citizens’ individual resources, what choice of political settlement treats citizens with equal concern? What choice would the fair-minded parent of them all make, for example?” (2008, p. 99; emphasis added). Now of course many will object to Dworkin’s analogy between a just political community and a fair-minded parent; I too find the analogy problematic. But for our purposes here, what is relevant is that for Dworkin, the social obligation to display equal concern is akin to a parent’s obligation insofar as it is a substantive obligation to actively promote certain individuals’ interests and good. It is not, therefore, merely the formal ideal of treating like cases alike, for that formal ideal could be satisfied by a bedroom-allocation rule that says “The youngest child, whoever he or she happens to be, shall get whatever bedroom remains after all older members of the family have made their choice.” Suppose, then, that Dworkin’s and Miller’s so-called duties of concern are indeed properly interpreted as duties of specific beneficence toward fellow citizens. We now must ask where those duties come from. What justifies them? 3. JUSTIFYING EQUAL CONCERN Here is Dworkin’s main argument for why a duty of equal concern is at the heart of social justice: 12 We extract people’s money or property through taxes, and we put them in jail or even, in our country, kill them when they do not do what we command. We not only do all this but claim a right to do it: we expect our fellow citizens to treat our collective demands as creating not just threats but moral obligations, the demanding moral obligation to obey our law. No single individual has any such power over other individuals. Our government claims all of it. (2008, p. 95) A legitimate government must treat all those over whom it claims dominion not just with a measure of concern but with equal concern. (p. 97) Dworkin here grounds a political community’s duty to display equal concern toward its members in the coercively enforced commands issued by the community (or by its official agents). He claims that the community’s commands are illegitimate unless they are accompanied by the display of a robust and equal measure of concern for each member. Yet even if Dworkin is correct in this, so far he has stated only a necessary condition of legitimate coercion, not a sufficient condition. After all, it would surely be objectionable for one society to invade and conquer another, even if afterwards it displayed the same degree of positive concern for those it conquered as it displays for its own members. So what further condition gives a political community the right to issue coercively-backed commands in the first place? Dworkin imagines being asked a similar question by a laissez-faire libertarian. In response he says: Of course we can, if that is what the majority of us wish, create a minimalist government with few powers to do anything except maintain a police force and armies and raise only the taxes necessary to those limited powers. But . . . we would therefore have the responsibility of showing how our decision to create a minimal state, when we might have created a government with much greater powers to help our poorer fellow citizens, treats all of us with equal concern. (2008, p. 100) This still seems to beg the question. Dworkin claims that a minimalist government would fail to show adequate concern for its members, but he still does not explain where these robust duties of concern come from in the first place. The welfare state institutions that Dworkin wants to justify are required only if robust duties of concern already exist. But Dworkin has not given us reason 13 to think these duties exist prior to the existence of the robust political relationships that a welfare state introduces. This is a problem that Miller explicitly takes up in his own concern-based approach to social justice. Miller writes: Because of the dependence of political duties of concern for compatriots on the nature of their shared political life, I will concentrate on one special case, the exercise of the functions characteristic of government in modern developed countries. . . . Prior to investigating the moral consequences of this state activity, the modern state’s engagement in such functionings must be justified. . . . One can create a broad enough justification by exploiting a grain of truth in the argument from mutual benefit. In modern circumstances, every compatriot’s rational self-interest supports an extensive set of government tasks, shaping compatriots’ prospects of self-advancement in profoundly important ways. (Miller 2010, pp. 40–41) So whereas Dworkin moves from the idea of robust concern to the justification of more-than- minimal governmental functionings, Miller moves from the idea of more-than-minimal governmental functionings to the requirement of robust concern. And to get the argument off the ground, Miller claims that the more-than-minimal government functionings are initially justified by reference to the rational self-interest of those who will be constrained by the resulting coercively enforced arrangements. As he puts it: Libertarian defenders of capitalism say that they advocate the Nightwatchman State, implying that defense against burglars is the epitome of the state’s legitimate functioning. But this restriction would be the death of modern capitalism. Everyone in a modern capitalist economy has a vital interest in state involvement, often with prolific public funding, in a variety of unnightwatchmanlike functions. (p. 43) Part of what Miller refers to here is what the political scientist Nathan Kelly calls “market- conditioning” institutions (Kelly 2009, p. 18). These include the central bank’s role in setting the key price in the entire economy, the interest rate; the central bank’s role as lender of last resort; the state’s bestowal of limited liability to corporate entities; and government granted monopolies in the form of patents. Very few libertarians argue seriously for abolishing these particular 14 market-conditioning institutions. Yet neither it is plausible to claim that individuals have a natural right to these devices of government. (How plausible is the claim that there’s a natural right to twelve years of market exclusivity for an invented product, after which competitors are free to copy one’s idea without any compensation whatsoever?) Rather, what justifies these governmental functions is that they are immensely effective tools for promoting the common good, conceived of as individuals’ similar yet separate interests in a political stability and economic prosperity. In addition to the major market-conditioning functions of government, Miller highlights further “unnightwatchmanlike” choices that will typically be reflected in the public policy of a prosperous democratic state. For example, there will likely be policies that answer such questions as “Under what conditions is a contract to provide skilled services marred by inadequate information about competence on the part of the buyer?” and “Under what circumstances does someone’s assertion of exclusive control over land or raw materials give rise to a right, and how extensive, permanent and transferable are these rights?” (p. 41). All of these policy issues cited so far involve questions to which it is in the interest of everyone to have settled answers. Yet any answer specific enough for public policy will also be rejected by many. This leads to the move that distinguishes Miller’s argument from Dworkin’s. For when public policy does impose determinate answers on a wide range of policy questions, each citizen inevitably faces what John Rawls termed “strains of commitment” (1971, sect. 29). These are the reasonable and understandable psychological strains that attend living under laws and policies one disagrees with or finds otherwise burdensome. According to Miller, it is these common yet poignant strains—what he called the strains of “institutional loyalty”—that generate further duties of concern in the form of duties to value one another’s “loyalty to the [political] project by 15 showing special loyalty to [fellow participants], displayed in special concern for their needs” (2010, p. 43). Thus, for Miller, while a broad array of coercive policies can be justified by reference to members’ self-interest, further coercive policies—those expressing robust concern— are justified as the way responsible social cooperators acknowledge one another’s mutual loyalty to a demanding and coercively structured political project. I believe that this last argument for a political community’s duties of concern for its members is superior to Dworkin’s, and that it is compelling in its own right. Furthermore, the seeds of a view like this can be found in Beauchamp and Childress’s discussion of how some duties of specific beneficence have their basis in the value of reciprocity. They write, “Reciprocity is the act or practice of making an appropriate and often proportional return” (2001, p. 213). And in a prior edition of Principles, Beauchamp and Childress claimed that “[M]any obligations of beneficence are appropriately justified by implicit arrangements underlying the necessary give-and-take of social life” (2001, p. 174). Of course, we have already seen that Beauchamp and Childress prescind from characterizing duties of specific beneficence as duties of justice, whereas Dworkin and Miller explicitly cast their discussions in those terms. But apart from that difference, Dworkin’s and Miller’s accounts can, I think, be viewed as fleshing out a line of argument that already exists in the bioethics literature but that is not as fully developed there. At this point, it is necessary to address an important question triggered by Miller’s account and by Beauchamp and Childress’s description of reciprocity as the practice of making an “often proportional return.” The question asks whether, by tying duties of concern and specific beneficence to loyal cooperation, a view like Miller’s entails that those who contribute more should receive more than equal concern. After all, Miller’s is an approach on which what 16 one is owed (specific beneficence) is determined by what one does (give loyal and burdensome social cooperation). So shouldn’t more go to those who give more? I want to offer four replies to this important question. The first thing to note is that Miller’s account underscores two features of modern democratic societies, and only the second of these is tied to individuals’ social contributions. These two features again are: (1) the fact that a complex of rules governing social cooperation is coercively enforced by all upon all (this is the feature that Dworkin also highlights); and (2) the fact that life-long, coercively structured social cooperation inevitably brings poignant strains of commitment in its wake. The first feature focuses on the ways in which fellow citizens shape each other’s lives and prospects by supporting coercive laws and policies. A reasonable claim here is that in helping to coercively structure another’s life, one shows full respect for him only if coercion is accompanied by positive concern for how his life goes. Thus even if the premise referring to strains of commitment were removed, there would still be some basis for requiring specific beneficence toward those whose lives one helps to shape and structure. Second, when we turn to the distinctive element of Miller’s account that is tied to cooperation and contribution—the element concerning institutional loyalty and strains of commitment—one must be careful not to draw arbitrary distinctions between individuals’ levels of contribution. For example, the account is decidedly not equivalent to an economistic approach that assesses social productivity by looking at wages as the quantifiable measure of individuals’ economic contribution.5 That sort of approach ignores the pervasive reach of market- conditioning policies and the corresponding ways in which political stability and economic prosperity depend upon coercion, compliance, and cooperation at virtually all times and across 5 For a recent defense of such a view, see Mankiw 2009. For cogent critique, see Sen 1985, Schweickart 2002, and Freeman 2011. 17 virtually all spheres of life. It is arbitrary to single out just one sphere—market employment—as revealing one’s total social contribution. Yet once one seeks to take account of all relevant spheres in which individuals’ compliance and cooperation contribute to a well-functioning democratic society, it becomes difficult to claim that any one person’s overall contribution is greater than any other’s. For example, those who earn much less than others often face distinct strains of commitment just on that account. Further, even when it does seem clear that certain people contribute more than certain others, a third consideration dulls that observation’s moral force. For in most spheres of social life, one’s ability to contribute is profoundly affected by the circumstances one finds oneself in, and the circumstances one finds oneself in often reflect historical injustice. This observation is particularly relevant for prominent cases involving those who violate rather than comply with coercively imposed laws and those who occupy prominent and important social and economic roles. If, for example, past discrimination, dispossession, or social marginalization affects one’s abilities and willingness to participate in the morally important give-and-take of social and economic life, then it would be wrong (1) to hold the effects of that injustice against those who were adversely affected by it and (2) to praise the inordinate contributions of who were helped by it. If poverty begets disaffection (as it does) and if privilege begets social and economic capital (as it does), then a morally responsible political community will seek to calibrate the strength of its specific beneficence by attending both to social contribution and to potentially unjust background factors that render individuals differentially able to contribute in the first place. This conclusion suggests that a principle of specific beneficence must be combined with other principles of justice so that individuals are not held responsible for failing to make contributions when that failure is influenced by prior or ongoing injustice. These considerations 18 pull the account back in the direction of equal concern, for if past injustice shapes individuals’ contributions, then holding this against the victims of injustice is an unjust form of double jeopardy. The fourth and final response to the claim that unequal contributions call for unequal concern acknowledges that some human beings, in particular those with profound cognitive disabilities, are mostly unable to contribute to society even under the most favorable conditions. But to acknowledge this is not yet to concede that such individuals are owed nothing under justice. The equal concern account, like Buchanan’s own account of enforced general beneficence, purports to describe just one central source of enforceable societal obligation. As Buchanan stressed, there is good reason to seek to combine diverse sources of obligation to yield wider ranging demands. Whether other sources are available is a further question for moral theory that I cannot take up here. But it is nevertheless a mistake to reject a source of social obligation simply because it alone cannot achieve the full coverage that one might reasonably want. I conclude, then, that there is a good case to be made for the egalitarian aspect of the equal concern account of societal duties of specific beneficence. My goal in this section has been to explain how Dworkin’s and Miller’s views connect up with the idea of specific beneficence, and how one might go about “scaling up” duties of specific beneficence to the societal level. For my part, when I reflect upon the nature of the positive, health-related duties I intuitively believe I have to fellow citizens, they do strike me as duties of beneficence, duties to show active concern for their interests and good. But since there are people around the world who are much worse off than most of my fellow citizens, the duties I intuitively feel I have to my compatriots must be ones of specific beneficence that, if genuine, justify focusing at least some efforts at home rather 19 than abroad. This in turn calls for an explanation of why specific duties like this should exist in the first place. The line of argument I have set out grounds these duties in the ways in which I help to coercively shape the lives of my compatriots, and the ways in which I simultaneously benefit from their constrained cooperation and compliance. 4. FROM SPECIFIC BENEFICENCE TO HEALTH CARE POLICY When it comes to justifying a legal right to a decent minimum of health care, the equal concern approach offers distinct advantages over Buchanan’s general beneficence argument. Buchanan recognized that some might accept his argument’s theoretical foundation while still rejecting his domestically-focused conclusion. For if the argument is largely predicated upon an enforceable duty of general beneficence, why focus on “the needy who dwell within the borders of a particular nation-state” (1984, p. 76)? In response, Buchanan claimed that there are no principled reasons to focus at home rather than abroad. Rather, there are “pragmatic” reasons that justify “a practical concession to the difficulties of being beneficent in an imperfect world” (p. 76). By contrast, if within-border obligations are primarily underwritten by duties of specific beneficence, as the equal concern approach has it, then one would not have to rely so heavily on “pragmatic” reasons to give some deference to national needs. This would in turn strengthen the argument for a domestic decent minimum of health care. The existence of specific duties of beneficence toward compatriots would also strengthen a recent argument for U.S. health reform made by David DeGrazia. DeGrazia claims that “Americans care deeply about achieving universal coverage, sensibly containing costs, protecting patient freedom, and preserving high-quality care.” He adds that “There is more support for these goals, surely, than for any particular theory of justice” (2008, p. 32). DeGrazia 20 concludes that it is unwise to invoke theories of justice in support of health reform; one should instead simply invoke the four items on DeGrazia’s list of health care “goals.” But then what is to be said when one discovers—as one surely will—disagreement over DeGrazia’s first health care goal, that of achieving universal coverage? Here is DeGrazia’s answer: “Not to consider universal coverage a high priority verges on the misanthropic” (p. 32). Another way to say this, of course, is that not to consider universal coverage a high priority is to lack minimal beneficence. But now consider the (admittedly quite unrealistic) scenario in which a misanthrope is successfully shamed by DeGrazia’s charge of misanthropy and now wants to focus her newfound beneficence on more dire needs abroad. What can DeGrazia say to get this reformed person on board with the four U.S. health care goals? One thing he could say, if he accepts societal duties of specific beneficence, is that to neglect serious but less dire needs at home would amount to flouting distinctive duties to compatriots. Suppose I am right that the equal concern account successfully establishes societal duties of specific beneficence. And suppose that, given my initial assumption of the importance of health for well-being and opportunities, there is a strong presumption in favor of providing a decent minimum of health care to all. What then should the decent minimum include? Buchanan’s answer is that this question cannot be specified in detail prior to subjecting it to “some fair procedure for reaching a social decision” (1984, p. 78). That is roughly my answer too, but Buchanan claims that only his view “can warmly welcome the lack of a principled specification.” The equal concern view must, he suggests, “accept it begrudgingly as an embarrassing theoretical lacuna” (pp. 77–78). This is because on Buchanan’s view, citizens’ duties of beneficence are not duties of justice that correlate with rights, but are instead duties of charity that “are imperfect duties: by their very nature they are not precisely delineated” (p. 77). 21 Is Buchanan right that the demands of equal concern, if they are demands of justice, must be precisely specifiable? Earlier I quoted Mill who conceptually tied duties of justice to individuals’ correlative claims. If the connection with claims is a hallmark of duties of justice, then social duties of specific beneficence fit the bill, for on the equal concern account each individual does have a strong claim on the beneficence of the political community as a whole. I do however admit that there will be a good deal of indeterminacy when moving from foundational demands of equal concern to their practical implementation. I see no way around that. But this is not the theoretical embarrassment Buchanan suggests it is. To use an illustrative example of Robert Audi’s, justice in a democracy quite obviously demands periodic free elections, but justice is clearly not specific about the maximal time interval between them (p. 152). Given that justice must tolerate at least some vagueness, we need an argument before we should conclude that the equal concern view cannot follow Buchanan’s own tack and rely upon a conscientious social dialogue to issue in more specific conclusions. Still, perhaps one way to make at least some progress translating the equal concern rationale for specific beneficence into policy is to imagine free market arrangements and then to ask whether they strike us as adequately expressing the beneficence required by justice. If not, we can ask what change would remove the deficiency. Something akin to this procedure has been employed by theorists as diverse as Dworkin (1993) and the conservative legal theorist Charles Fried (1978). Dworkin and Fried each agree that free market arrangements might need correction with respect to the potentially unjust distribution of external resources (such as income and wealth). To address this, each asks his reader to assume that the distribution of external resources is perfectly just according to the reader’s own criterion of what justice 22 requires here. Dworkin and Fried then ask: would it then be just to simply let individuals choose their preferred level of insurance from the options that emerge in a free market for health insurance? Dworkin’s answer is that such an arrangement fails to show adequate concern for those who will be denied affordable insurance because of health risks they are either born with or acquire through no fault of their own (2002, pp. 342–343; 2008, p. 114). Fried foresaw such an objection, and wrote: there is nothing in the [free market] insurance proposal which assumes that expensive measures will not be available in the unlikely case that we need them: if the occasion of need is really very unlikely, then one ought to be able to purchase a very high level of protection for a small premium. If, on the other hand, the “need” is very likely to occur and very likely to be expensive—imagine some elaborate way to retard the effects of normal aging—then why should one complain if vast social resources are not made available for this purpose? (1978, p. 128) The problem here is that Fried ducks the question at issue. The question is not whether social resources should be made available for a Peter Pan drug that keeps people young, but rather whether those who already have, say, cancer or diabetes—those whose risk is 100 percent— should face higher (and often prohibitively high) insurance prices just on that account. This question cannot be answered by noting, plausibly, that public subsidies for the Peter Pan drug would not be required by any reasonable approach to social beneficence. Rather, it seems fairly clear that a political community does not show even minimal beneficence toward a cancer victim if it justifies not helping him by citing an alleged analogy between him and the Peter Pan drug- seeker. This supports the conclusion that free markets for insurance, even when corrected for unfair distributions of income, do not yet display due beneficence toward those who face high and costly health risks through no fault of their own. Some policy instruments—e.g. guaranteed issue, community rating, insurance mandates, and subsidies—will be required to ensure that 23 those who need health care the most are not turned away by insurance companies’ prices or policies.6 This line of argument connects the demands of specific beneficence to what Paul Menzel has recently called a Just Sharing Principle (JSP). A JSP requires at least some robust sharing of “the financial burdens of illness.” On Menzel’s version of the JSP, it requires that “[t]he financial burdens of medical misfortunes ought to be shared equally by the well and the ill alike, unless individuals can be reasonably expected to control these misfortunes by their own choices” (2012, p. 584). Menzel grounds his JSP in a more fundamental moral principle that he calls Equal Opportunity for Welfare (EOW), which says: “People should not be worse off [in terms of welfare] than others through no fault or voluntary choice of their own.” EOW is thus a luck egalitarian principle. There are many versions of luck egalitarianism, but their common thread is the claim that inequalities are pro tanto unjust, unless they can be shown to result from the responsible choices of individuals. (Pro tanto here indicates that the injustice can be outweighed by other moral factors; for example, a policy that widens unchosen inequalities may nevertheless be all-things-considered just if the increase in inequality is morally outweighed by significant improvements in the well-being of the worst off.) Luck egalitarianism, therefore, sees (pro tanto) injustice in inequalities that result from “bad brute luck,” but not in inequalities that can be traced to individuals’ responsible choices or gambles. This approach stands in contrast to the beneficence-based view I have been exploring. For example, while it may be clear that proper beneficence does not require the provision of a Peter Pan drug (especially when there are so many other pressing needs in the population), it is not as obvious that beneficence can justly be withheld whenever individuals are responsible for their own plight. Indeed, a leading luck 6 These are central coverage-related policy instruments in the Patient Protection and Affordable Care Act of 2010, but they are certainly not the only way to achieve affordable universal coverage. 24 egalitarian, Shlomi Segall, agrees that luck egalitarian principles like EOW can be unduly harsh on those who are nevertheless at fault for their serious health needs. Segall concludes that principles like EOW must therefore be supplemented by “a prior duty to meet basic needs, including medical needs” (2009, p. 75). Segall’s social duty to meet basic needs has all the hallmarks of a duty of beneficence, and his reliance on it shows that luck egalitarianism is not the only basis available to underwrite a Just Sharing Principle. Distinct beneficence-based moral principles can play that role as well. In fact, concerns about the “harshness” of luck egalitarianism suggest that beneficence-based principles might be better suited to play that role than is a thoroughly choice-sensitive principle like Menzel’s EOW.7 A beneficence-based approach to social obligation can also be used to criticize Menzel’s JSP on a different score. As I noted, Menzel’s JSP calls for equal sharing of the financial burdens of illness “by the well and the ill alike.” But why call on the well, rather than on the well-to-do, to share burdens with the ill? Suppose Steve Jobs had lacked insurance when he was very sick. In that case, should a healthy 35 year old making $15,000, $35,000, or even $55,000 per year be called upon to share the burdens of Steve Jobs’ illness? That is seemingly what would be required by a principle enjoining equal sharing between the well and the ill. Yet it seems more plausible, and more consistent with the demands of beneficence, to require sharing between the rich and the ill. We should indeed care about what happens to Steve Jobs—he has a claim on our beneficence too—but we must also be sensitive to the effects that a Just Sharing Principle would have on the interests of those who would be forced to help him. When the person needing help is rich enough to provide all available care for himself, it is unclear why any sharing at all is called 7 I lack the space to discuss the difficult question of when individuals’ responsibility for their own ill health lessens or eliminates others’ duties of beneficence toward them. For further discussion of the so- called harshness objection to luck egalitarianism, see Anderson 1999 and Voigt 2007. 25 for.8 Likewise, when those who are sick are also very poorly off in terms of income, it seems reasonable to finance social beneficence through progressive taxation (which falls more heavily on the rich) rather than through a mechanism that targets the resources of healthy people, regardless of their income. Finally, let me stress that even if duties of specific beneficence do in fact ground social rights to health care, it does not follow that doctors have duties of specific beneficence toward their patients. As I have been understanding them, duties of beneficence are duties to promote another’s interests or good or well-being, broadly construed. But physicians’ duties should arguably be construed more narrowly, as duties to promote patients’ health, rather than patients’ well-being. To use an example I owe to Daniel Hausman, my physician has a stronger duty to help me gain access to a $50 tetanus shot than she does to help me gain access to $50 in cash. This is so even if I strongly and quite reasonably prefer the cash instead. So it must be stressed that my argument seeks to account for the fundamental duties of social justice that call for health-promoting social institutions. These fundamental duties can be duties of (specific) beneficence even if there are reasons to construe the downstream duties of physicians more narrowly. In this section I have sought to tease out some policy implications of the beneficence- based view that emerged from sections 2 and 3. But I have also openly admitted that there is unavoidable vagueness both in the strength of morally required specific beneficence and in the proper manner of its display. Buchanan suggested that vagueness along these dimensions fits better with an approach that views the relevant moral principles as principles of charity rather than principles of justice. I do not agree. Sometimes the demands of justice are just as vague as 8 Since Menzel’s discussion is pitched at the level of moral principle, I am here ignoring strategic considerations such as those connected to the slogan, “A program for the poor is a poor program.” 26 the demands of charity, as was illustrated by Audi’s example of the interval between free democratic elections. Thus while I do believe that individuals have assertable moral claims to societal beneficence, I do not believe that individuals can assert moral claims to specific amounts of health-related resources. Nevertheless, some Just Sharing Principles are more consonant with the equal concern account of specific beneficence than others, and I have suggested that a reasonable version of such a principle would justify public policy to shape health insurance markets and would call more upon the wealthy than on the healthy to share others’ financial burdens of illness. 5. CONCLUSION In this paper I have drawn on a distinction from bioethics and on an approach to social obligation from political philosophy to support the conclusion that political communities are under justice-based obligations of specific beneficence toward their members. Since I am forced to concede that these obligations are not as precisely specifiable as one would like, I sought (in section 4) to tease out some lessons for health policy that nevertheless strike me as consonant with the account I have set out. In particular, I agreed with Dworkin and Segall that duties of beneficence (Dworkin calls them duties of concern, Segall cites “basic needs”) can underwrite a Just Sharing Principle justifying at least some government involvement in health insurance markets. There are, however, many options in between a regime that only slightly improves upon the free market and a regime that is prepared to provide Fried’s Peter Pan drug to anyone that wants it. Should I be embarrassed that I cannot say which regime in between these is most just? All I can say is that I have been as specific as I can see how to be at present. At any rate, I 27 believe it is useful to sketch, even in a rudimentary way, a framework for justice in health care that provides an alternative (or supplement) to views grounded in luck egalitarianism (Menzel, Segall), general beneficence (Buchanan), or the simple avoidance of misanthropy (DeGrazia). One need not be a misanthrope to ask why one must take an especially active interest in the interests of certain others. The equal concern approach to justice in health care provides an answer, and it is an answer I think worth exploring further. ACKNOWLEDGMENTS For comments and discussion on material included here, I would like to thank Dan Hausman, Gordon Hull, Win-chiat Lee, John C. Moskop, and participants at the 2013 Junior Scholars in Bioethics Workshop at Wake Forest University. REFERENCES Anderson, Elizabeth S. 1999. What Is the Point of Equality? Ethics 109 (2): 287–337. Audi, Robert. 2004. The Good in the Right: A Theory of Intuition and Intrinsic Value. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Beauchamp, Tom L., and James F. Childress. 2001. Principles of Biomedical Ethics, 5th ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ———. 2013. Principles of Biomedical Ethics, 7th ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Broome, John. 2002. Measuring the Burden of Disease by Aggregating Well-Being. In Summary Measures of Population Health: Concepts, Ethics, Measurement and Applications, edited by Christopher J. L. Murray, Joshua A. Salomon, Colin D. Mathers, and Alan D. Lopez, 91–113. Geneva: World Health Organization. 28 Buchanan, Allen E. 1984. The Right to a Decent Minimum of Health Care. Philosophy and Public Affairs 13 (1): 55–78. Daniels, Norman. 1981. Health Care Needs and Distributive Justice. Philosophy and Public Affairs 10 (2): 146–79. DeGrazia, David. 2003. Common Morality, Coherence, and the Principles of Biomedical Ethics. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 13 (3): 219–30. ———. 2008. Single Payer Meets Managed Competition: The Case for Public Funding and Private Delivery. Hastings Center Report 38 (1): 23-33. Dworkin, Ronald. 1978. Taking Rights Seriously. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. ———. 1993. Justice in the Distribution of Health Care. McGill Law Journal 38 (4): 883–98. ———. 2002. Sovereign Virtue. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. ———. 2008. Is Democracy Possible Here? Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Freeman, Samuel. 2011. Capitalism in the Classical and High Liberal Traditions. Social Philosophy and Policy 28 (2): 19–55. Fried, Charles. 1978. Right and Wrong. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Gert, Bernard, Charles M. Culver, and Danner K. Clouser. 2006. Bioethics: A Systematic Approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Kelly, Nathan J. 2009. The Politics of Income Inequality in the United States. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Mankiw, N. Gregory. 2010. Spreading the Wealth Around: Reflections on Joe the Plumber. Eastern Economic Journal 36: 285–98. Menzel, Paul T. 2011. The Cultural Moral Right to a Basic Minimum of Accessible Health Care. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 21 (1): 79–119. 29 ———. 2012. Justice and Fairness: A Critical Element in US Health System Reform. The Journal of Law, Medicine & Ethics 40 (3): 582-597. Mill, John Stuart. (1861) 2006. Utilitarianism. In The Blackwell Guide to Mill’s Utilitarianism, edited by Henry R. West, 61–113. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing. Miller, Richard W. 2002. Too Much Inequality. Social Philosophy and Policy 19 (1): 275–313. ———. 2010. Globalizing Justice: The Ethics of Poverty and Power. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pogge, Thomas. 1999. A Global Resources Dividend. In Ethics of Consumption: The Good Life, Ethics and Global Stewardship, edited by David Crocker and Toby Linden, 501–30. Totowa, NJ: Rowman and Littlefield. Rawls, John. 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Ross, W. D. 1930. The Right and the Good. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Segall, Shlomi. 2009. Health, Luck, and Justice. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Sen, Amartya. 1980. Equality of What? In The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, vol. 1, edited by Sterling M. McMurrin, 195–220. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ———. 1985. The Moral Standing of the Market. Social Philosophy and Policy 2 (2): 1–19. Schweickart, David. 2002. After Capitalism. Plymouth, UK: Rowman & Littlefield. Voigt, Kristin. 2007. The Harshness Objection: Is Luck Egalitarianism Too Harsh on the Victims of Option Luck? Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 10 (4): 389–407. work_bva57ur6cjhlbpbbymvzbzoj5m ---- Microsoft Word - AJCD-social justice.doc Final and authorised version first published in the Australian Journal of Career Development in  Volume 14, number 2, published by the Australian Council for Educational Research.  Copyright © 2005 Australian Council for Educational Research. A UNIVERSITY CAREER SERVICE AND SOCIAL JUSTICE PETER McILVEEN, BRADLEY EVERTON, & JOHN CLARKE University of Southern Queensland January 2005 For submission to: Australian Journal of Career Development Special Edition: Career Development and Higher Education in Australia Guest Editor: Dr Anna Lichtenberg Final and authorised version first published in the Australian Journal of Career Development in  Volume 14, number 2, published by the Australian Council for Educational Research.  Copyright © 2005 Australian Council for Educational Research. ABSTRACT This paper describes the social justice activities facilitated by a university careers service. The paper includes a discussion on the relationship between social justice and career development in higher education. Working examples of the activities provided by the career service focus upon the delivery of career-related services to students who are represented by the major equity groups identified within the Australian higher education sector. The importance of theoretically informed practice and collaboration between campus agencies is emphasised as a means of achieving social justice outcomes. Final and authorised version first published in the Australian Journal of Career Development in  Volume 14, number 2, published by the Australian Council for Educational Research.  Copyright © 2005 Australian Council for Educational Research. Within the career development literature, social justice has been described as the actions that advance society and advocate for the equal access to resources for disempowered people (O’Brien, 2001). Career development and social justice are not historical strangers. Hartung and Blustein (2002) and O’Brien (2001) described how one of the founders of the discipline of career development, Frank Parsons, was committed to connecting career decision-making and social justice in his work in the early part of the 20th century. The connection has not been ignored - major contemporary texts on career development, counselling and education routinely make reference to the needs of ‘special groups’ (e.g., Herr, Cramer & Niles, 2004). Despite the clear impact that career development can have on influencing social mobility and change, Hartung and Blustein (2002) asserted that the discipline of career development was in need of a new paradigm that clearly recognised the unequal distribution of societal resources. In order to fully account for social justice issues, they suggested that counsellors should expand their practices beyond the focus of the individual. In this vein, Hansen (2003) and Herr (2003) argued that (in the American context) career counselling practice should interact with public policy. Careers industry standards vary throughout the world; however, most professional organisations make reference to the needs of all persons and emphasise the needs of those who are disadvantaged. For example, the International Association for Educational and Vocational Guidance (IAEVG) declared that: • Each person - regardless of gender, education, race, religion, age or occupational status - should have free and easy access to educational and vocational guidance so that their individual capabilities and skills can be identified and developed to enable them to undertake adequate education, vocational training and employment, to adapt to changing individual and Final and authorised version first published in the Australian Journal of Career Development in  Volume 14, number 2, published by the Australian Council for Educational Research.  Copyright © 2005 Australian Council for Educational Research. social life situations and to participate fully in the social and economic life of their community. • Special target groups, eg, persons with disabilities and social disadvantages, should be provided with career counselling that uses appropriate methods and counselling that take into account their particular needs and communication requirement (IAEVG, 2001). The United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organisation (UNESCO) (1998) produced a handbook on career counselling specific to higher education. In that handbook, UNESCO declares a number of assumptions, including: • People have the ability and opportunity to make career choices for their lives. The amount of freedom in choices is partially dependent upon the social, economic, and cultural context of individuals. • Opportunities and choices should be available for all people, regardless of sex, socio-economic class, religion, disability, sexual orientation, age, or cultural background (UNESCO, 1998, p. 4). These assumptions were established as key attitudes to be taken up by careers practitioners operating within the higher education sector. Within the Australian context, Hughes (1995) was critical of career development practices within the school sector and suggested that there was a risk of maintaining social structures with inherent features of inequalities. Patton and McMahon (1997, 1999) invigorated career development theory and practice within the Australian social justice and equity context. Their Systems Theory Framework (STF) has emphasised a confluence of social, economic and environmental factors that transcends the intrapsychic factors that have been the traditional foci of major theories and practices of career development. For example, Collett (1997) has used Final and authorised version first published in the Australian Journal of Career Development in  Volume 14, number 2, published by the Australian Council for Educational Research.  Copyright © 2005 Australian Council for Educational Research. the STF to explicate the problems of rurality and its impact upon the education of school children; and Sarra (1997) likewise for indigenous persons; and Taylor (1997) for the issue of socio-economic status and participation in higher education. As a result of the STF’s broader conceptualisation of career development, variables that induce or potentiate problems associated with social justice are readily accounted. AUSTRALIAN HIGHER EDUCATION In describing a set of preferred principles for a higher education system in Australia, the Commonwealth Minister for Education stated that: There must be equality of opportunity in higher education to allow individuals to fulfil their potential, regardless of their personal circumstances and backgrounds. There should be no systemic barriers to participation. There should be provision for the varying needs of students from different backgrounds (Nelson, 2002, p.2). Successive Commonwealth Governments have variously identified equity groups that represent individuals who fall into categories of social disadvantage. These equity- groups include: indigenous students; women studying in non-traditional areas; students with a disability; students from a rural or isolated region; students from language backgrounds other than English; and students from low socio-economic status backgrounds (Dawkins, 1990). The equity groups have been broadly studied and reported upon with respect to individuals’ entry into, and progress through the higher education system in Australia. Fortunately there has been some progress in improving access, retention, and progress for many groups (e.g., Abbott-Chapman, Hughes, & Wyld, 1991; Australian Education Council, 1991; Department of Education, Training & Youth Final and authorised version first published in the Australian Journal of Career Development in  Volume 14, number 2, published by the Australian Council for Educational Research.  Copyright © 2005 Australian Council for Educational Research. Affairs, 1999a; National Board of Employment, Education and Training, 1994; Nelson, 2002; Senate Standing Committee on Employment, Education and Training, 1990; Williams, Long, Carpenter & Hayden, 1993). The Commonwealth Government has required universities to respond to the needs of these equity groups through the development and implementation of Equity Plans and Indigenous Education Strategies (DETYA, 1999b; 1999c). Furthermore, the Government has monitored institutional performance as expressed through the performance of students in equity groups relative to the student population as a whole (Martin, 1994). UNIVERSITY OF SOUTHERN QUEENSLAND (USQ) USQ is a multi-campus, non-elite, community-focused regional university, which developed from a background as a College of Advanced Education with a heavy emphasis on employing flexible modes of study. With this background it is not surprising that USQ’s students come from a wide diversity of social, cultural and location backgrounds which include a high proportion of 'first generation' learners (i.e., students who are the first in their family to attend university), 'second chance' learners (i.e., students who come to university study for the first time as adults) and students from identified equity groups – particularly low SES students, students from rural and isolated areas and indigenous students. Learning and teaching represents the USQ’s core function. In this context, social justice at USQ is most clearly embodied in the provision of opportunities for access with success to relevant career paths for a diverse student constituency. All of USQ's social justice strategies emanate from this core theme. The development of linkages and networks with other educational providers serves as a basis for outreach, taster and articulation programs; access and transition strategies include recognition of Final and authorised version first published in the Australian Journal of Career Development in  Volume 14, number 2, published by the Australian Council for Educational Research.  Copyright © 2005 Australian Council for Educational Research. prior learning, scholarships programs, orientation and first-year programs; strategies promoting retention and progression centre on inclusive curriculum and assessment, and a wide range of student support services; and the successful transition into employment requires careers education that begins with the University's first contact with the student. Early exposure to careers education is seen as a key social justice strategy that operates at a number of levels. It is well established that students with a stronger career focus are more likely to persist in their studies - hence early careers advice has been used for many years in US higher education as a basis persistence strategy (Tinto, 1998). This effect is, in part, due to ensuring that students are pursuing a study route that is right for them – improving persistence through improving the fit between the student and the course of study. However, other factors also come into play. For example, by positioning students to gain a greater understanding of the value of the qualification which they are working towards, early careers education has been found to be particularly valuable for first generation and second chance learners who may otherwise be considered at high risk of dropping out, in part due to a tendency to doubt the value of a university education and/or their capacity to achieve it. Factors such as choosing the optimal course program are also critical for these groups. Careers education is also critical to improving the knowledge and confidence (and hence persistence) of particular disadvantaged groups who are prone to discrimination or particular hardship in the workforce, such as indigenous students, students from non-English speaking backgrounds and students with disabilities. Overall, careers education empowers disadvantaged students through improving their knowledge base and confidence, and ensuring that they are maximally positioned to know what career they want and how they need to go about securing it. Final and authorised version first published in the Australian Journal of Career Development in  Volume 14, number 2, published by the Australian Council for Educational Research.  Copyright © 2005 Australian Council for Educational Research. By providing strategies that encourage a diverse range of students to persist and progress successfully in their studies, and through to employment, careers education provides a major plank in USQ's overall social justice strategy. These strategies are of particular relevance to high-risk groups, such as first generation learners, second chance learners and learners from identified equity groups. USQ CAREERS EMPLOYMENT & WELFARE USQ Careers Employment & Welfare (the Service) is a unit within the university’s Student Services. The Service provides individual career counselling, career education, campus employment services, financial services, and accommodation information. The two other units within Student Services are: Counselling & Health, which provides personal counselling, nursing, medical, and academic skills support; and International Student Support, which provides additional support for international students, such as arrival and departure, visa processing, cross-cultural counselling and education. Organisational change The provision of welfare support, however, has not been a traditional component of careers and employment services. The welfare support provided by Student Services focussed mainly upon providing accommodation, financial support and crisis counselling support, and was an odd bedfellow for the careers and employment activities. The integration of Welfare was crucial for the overall operation of the Service. Over the past three years the Service has reviewed its core mission and has transmuted the welfare support. Welfare is now integral to the mission of the overall Final and authorised version first published in the Australian Journal of Career Development in  Volume 14, number 2, published by the Australian Council for Educational Research.  Copyright © 2005 Australian Council for Educational Research. career development goals of the Service, and represents a set of service activities that have influence the careers and employment elements of the Service. This organisational revision was partly guided by application of the STF (Patton and McMahon, 1997, 1999), which provided the theoretical validation and conceptualisation of the nexus between social and economic disadvantage and the career development services within the university context. A previous position of Welfare Counsellor provided the services of accommodation support, financial support and crisis counselling. Through a process of consultation and realignment of service responsibilities, these activities were changed considerably. The position was retitled from Welfare Counsellor to Psychologist, Careers and Equity or Social Worker, Careers and Equity (depending upon the profession of the incumbent). The use of Careers and Equity was specifically included to signal the nexus between career development and the provision of services to alleviate disadvantage. The position description mandates the incumbent to provide counselling and educational programs that facilitate students’ progress in university studies and overcomes career barriers related to socio-economic background. The bulk of accommodation activities were reduced and devolved to the Administrative Officer. Crisis counselling was retained, but reduced in the number of allocated hours, and became a backup support for the other units of Student Services. Financial support consisted of the assessment of students’ needs and the provision of short-term loans. This activity was retained, but modified. The assessment process was changed to include more emphasis upon the relationship of a loan to a particular student’s career and educational plans. This required a more comprehensive analysis of the presenting problem and included psychosocial assessment with respect to Final and authorised version first published in the Australian Journal of Career Development in  Volume 14, number 2, published by the Australian Council for Educational Research.  Copyright © 2005 Australian Council for Educational Research. career, studies and their relationship to financial competence and hardship. The position also took on a significant role in the assessment and management of scholarships, which are discussed later in this paper. Providing support for casual employment was added into the position description. This entailed an educational perspective through which casual employment underpinned the acquisition of skills for students’ ultimate career and employment plans after university. Furthermore, responsibility for the provision of career education programs to students from the major equity groups was included in the position description. Moreover, these career education activities were to be integrated with the work of the Psychologist, Careers and Industry, the position primarily responsible for the bulk of work relating to career counselling and education. INTEGRATED SOCIAL JUSTICE ACTIVITIES What follows is a description of the service activities specific to the social justice agenda of the Service. The ethos, development and implementation of these activities were guided by the STF and the aims and principles of the IAEVG and UNESCO. Essentially, the Service is committed to the notion that university career services are powerful vehicles for social justice ideals and objectives (O’Brien, 2001). Rural school children and parents USQ is a major provider of higher education to regional Australians. Rural students’ transition into and through higher education is a significant issue with respect to failure and retention. The Service developed a career education program that has engaged rural high school students in an intensive, experiential process in which they Final and authorised version first published in the Australian Journal of Career Development in  Volume 14, number 2, published by the Australian Council for Educational Research.  Copyright © 2005 Australian Council for Educational Research. are immersed in university (McIlveen, Ford & Everton, in press). The residential experience included educational sessions on career exploration, the actual process of being a student at university (e.g., attending lectures, renting away from home), and the social experiences related to living in a city. The Service has also maintained a program of visiting rural schools within the Darling Downs region. These visits include career education sessions with senior school children during the day and with parents at night. The visits are specifically designed for first-generation families, who have not been exposed to higher education. Indigenous school children The University’s Kumbari Ngurpai Lag Higher Education Centre provides comprehensive academic support for indigenous students. Part of its brief involves the provision of preparatory courses to students. The Service collaborates with the Kumbari Ngurpai Lag in providing a career education workshop to high school children who are brought to campus to discover university (similar to the program for rural students mentioned previously). Students with disability The Service conducted an employment forum for university students with a disability. The forum was founded upon the notion that the employment-related knowledge and self-confidence of students with a disability could be enhanced by linking students, with one another, employers, employment agencies, State and Commonwealth Government agencies, and with key staff of the university’s careers service. The forum allowed for intensive networking and contained presentations on specific skills Final and authorised version first published in the Australian Journal of Career Development in  Volume 14, number 2, published by the Australian Council for Educational Research.  Copyright © 2005 Australian Council for Educational Research. and knowledge required for entry (and re-entry) into the workforce (e.g., disclosure of disability). Evaluation of the forum indicated its strengths in terms of content and process (McIlveen, Cameron, McLachlan & Gunn, in press). The Counselling and Health unit of Student Services, in collaboration with the Regional Disability Liaison Officer stationed at USQ, has established the Tertiary Taster Program for high school students with a disability. The Service contributes a career education seminar to this residential program. The students learn about their career options and are guided in selecting tertiary education courses. Females in non-traditional disciplines The university operates a successful program for high school girls that aims to immerse them in the career and educational possibilities of mathematics, science and technologies. The Service collaborates with this program and provides a career education seminar that focuses upon expanding the girls’ view of their career potential and futures. Gender issues are also sensitively considered within the scope of individual career counselling for women returning to the workforce or attempting to realign their career. Financial assistance and scholarships Students in general require considerable financial support and assistance in finding stable and manageable casual employment (Long & Hayden, 2001). To this end the Service manages a loan scheme that provides small, short-term, interest-free loans to student on behalf of the university, for the purchase of educational materials or emergency items (e.g., medicine). The Psychologist, Careers and Equity, administers these loans in conjunction with a review panel, consisting of the Service Manager and Final and authorised version first published in the Australian Journal of Career Development in  Volume 14, number 2, published by the Australian Council for Educational Research.  Copyright © 2005 Australian Council for Educational Research. the Manager of the Counselling and Health unit of Student Services. The assessment process for a loan requires standardized financial information and a demonstrated capacity to repay the loan. Moreover, the assessment interview takes a holistic view of a person’s circumstances, similar to the STF model, in order to determine the relevance of the financial support in context of the student’s overall career and educational status. The Psychologist is also responsible for guiding the student’s who take a loan on the process of better financial management, through individual and group-based education, and on securing part-time or casual employment for future needs. The Service manages eight undergraduate scholarships: the Commonwealth Learning Scholarships (Commonwealth Education Cost Scholarship and Commonwealth Accommodation Scholarship); Chancellor’s Scholarship; School- leaver Scholarship; Non-School Leaver Scholarship; Indigenous Student Scholarship; Distance Education Scholarship; and the Robin Yong Scholarship. The majority of these scholarships have financial hardship, personal hardship, or membership of an equity group as selection criteria. The assessment process is conducted by a panel, which is convened by the Manager of the Service. The Psychologist, Careers and Equity, takes a lead role in providing an expert opinion on the applicants’ situation as it relates to their needs and career and educational status. Tertiary Preparation Program USQ has been a leader in the provision of preparatory education for students who are unable to enter university via the standard pathway of high school and tertiary entrance score. The University’s Tertiary Preparation Program (TPP) has demonstrated its efficacy in properly preparing students for undergraduate studies Final and authorised version first published in the Australian Journal of Career Development in  Volume 14, number 2, published by the Australian Council for Educational Research.  Copyright © 2005 Australian Council for Educational Research. (Clarke, Bull & Clarke, 2004a, 2004b). An important feature of the TPP is a career educational module through which the individual studying the course completes a career assessment and develops educational pathways for their career success. This assignment work is completed under the instruction of the TPP Career Counsellor. The Service and the academic unit that offers TPP collaboratively manage the position of TPP Career Counsellor. Community career education Career education is not widely available in the regional communities of the University. The Service provides free career education seminars in collaborative arrangement with the University’s marketing and public relations unit. The content of the public seminars focuses upon the nature of university life, career information and assessment, and how to enter university. Although supported by the marketing department, the career education work is provided as a professional community service and without bias toward USQ. These seminars are focussed primarily upon non-school leavers and potential first-generation students who would not ordinarily consider higher education an option for their career. To support its work in assisting individuals who were unfamiliar with processes and occasional abstruse discourse of universities, the Service published a community education booklet, the Family Guide to USQ (Ford & McIlveen, 2003). This product was firmly directed at the parents of first-generation students. Its was produced through the support of key stakeholders (e.g., rural parents associations) that were able to specify which elements of higher education were in need of clarification for the new-comer. The booklet’s content ranges widely; from explaining the terminology of university, to possible career outcomes for particular programs, to the Final and authorised version first published in the Australian Journal of Career Development in  Volume 14, number 2, published by the Australian Council for Educational Research.  Copyright © 2005 Australian Council for Educational Research. pragmatics of renting and paying for textbooks. This Guide complements other supportive information available on-line and in print. Committees and organisational communication The Service has embarked on a strategy of internal liaison and consultation in order to assure its goals of providing career services to students from disadvantaged backgrounds. This is an ongoing activity that requires considerable attention within a dynamic organisation replete with competing and evolving priorities. The Manager of the Service sits on the Vice-Chancellor’s Committee on Student Support and Equity. This committee provides the organisational forum through which the needs of disadvantaged students can be presented and through which relevant policy or recommendations can be developed. This Committee also subsumes the Disability Advisory Sub-committee. This committee provides an avenue through which career development issues can be raised. The Service has relied heavily upon collaboration as a means of initiating and implementing social justice activities. This entails a commitment to working with other, sometimes disparate, organisational units. New and emerging activities The Service has commenced negotiations to develop an indigenous student mentorship program through which senior students will mentor first-year students and high school students. This program aims to provide significant role modelling to encourage indigenous students from a local high school to consider higher education and to encourage current university students who feel discouraged in their studies. Final and authorised version first published in the Australian Journal of Career Development in  Volume 14, number 2, published by the Australian Council for Educational Research.  Copyright © 2005 Australian Council for Educational Research. Toowoomba, and the University, has welcomed refugees into the city. As a multicultural education centre, the University provides an important source of support for refugees. There are considerable cultural issues that need to be addressed to better facilitate these new Australians’ entry into the workforce; admission to a degree is not the only solution. They require support in learning and engaging with the discourse of career and employment within the Australian context. The Psychologist, Careers and Equity, commenced the first round of consultations with a pilot group of undergraduate students were holders of a humanitarian visa or were recently granted citizenship. The aim of the project is to enhance the students’ career development and their capacity to enter the workforce as graduates. The University has established a Pro-Vice Chancellor portfolio for social justice and regional engagement. The creation of this PVC role opens up considerable opportunities for the Service with respect to engaging with the University as a whole. It is envisaged the Service will actively pursue the aims of this portfolio in an attempt to bring about best practice in social justice and further collaborate with university agencies. DISCUSSION There is neither a comprehensive nor definitive guide for the implementation of social justice ideas or strategies within the career development sector of Australian higher education. Nevertheless, we contend that the practice of career development within higher education should reflect theory and that it should be used to revise existing practices and to implement new practices. This paper describes a limited range of proactive professional services that are driven by the idea of linking career development and social justice within higher education. An important feature of the Final and authorised version first published in the Australian Journal of Career Development in  Volume 14, number 2, published by the Australian Council for Educational Research.  Copyright © 2005 Australian Council for Educational Research. work presented here is its implicit relationship with the Systems Theory Framework and the aims and principles of the IAEVG (2001) and UNESCO (1998). There are of course limitations to the amount and quality of social change work that can be done, given the exigencies of a busy career service. The extent to which an organisation can introduce social change work is constrained by resources and attitude, rather than by standards or ideals, as these are readily available (e.g., DEST, 2004; IAEVG, 2001; UNESCO, 1998). In terms of resources, the examples presented here are generally cost-efficient and can be readily established within other university settings and so mitigate against the perennial issue of limited resources. Furthermore, it is our experience that collaboration with organisations that are not agents of social action can produce positive, cost-efficient outcomes. It is therefore imperative that that a university career service maintains links and networks with other internal and external agencies (e.g., employers) to develop a broad understanding of social justice issues within the community. Our example of working with university marketing and public relations staff is indicative of this point. Furthermore, we contend that it is the responsibility of the careers service to engage with university organisational dynamics to bring about social justice initiatives, rather than rely upon a top-down approach of waiting for direction and resources. Career development practitioners are powerful gatekeepers and channels into the higher education system. We therefore encourage career development practitioners to learn about the key issues of equity and disadvantage that have a significant impact upon the career potentials and outcomes of students. There is a variety of equity-related resources that are of value to career practitioners. We recommend the Commonwealth Department of Education, Science and Training (2004) website that contains resources pertaining to equity issues in higher education. Final and authorised version first published in the Australian Journal of Career Development in  Volume 14, number 2, published by the Australian Council for Educational Research.  Copyright © 2005 Australian Council for Educational Research. This site contains links to crucial documents that guide and underpin Australian policies and practices pertaining to higher education. Final and authorised version first published in the Australian Journal of Career Development in  Volume 14, number 2, published by the Australian Council for Educational Research.  Copyright © 2005 Australian Council for Educational Research. REFERENCES Australian Education Council. (1991). Young people’s participation in post- compulsory education & training. Canberra: Australian Government Publishing Service. Abbott-Chapman, J., Hughes, P., Wyld, C. (1991). Improving access of disadvantaged youth to higher education. Evaluations and Investigations Program. Department of Employment, Education and Training. Canberra: Australian Government Publishing Service. Clarke, J. A., Bull, D. D., & Clarke, J. R. (2004a). USQ's tertiary preparation program (TPP): more than 15 years of evolution in distance preparatory / bridging programs. Manuscript submitted for publication. Clarke, J. A., Bull, D. D., & Clarke, J. R. (2004b). Changes in the pedagogical and administrative approaches used in the USQ tertiary preparation program, 1989-2004. Manuscript submitted for publication. Collett, I. (1997). Implications of rural location on career development. . In W. Patton & M. McMahon (Eds.), Career development in practice. A systems theory perspective (pp. 71-82). Sydney: New Hobsons Press. Dawkins, J. (1990) A fair chance for all: Higher education that’s within everyone’s reach. Canberra: Department of Employment, Education and Training. Department of Education, Science and Training. (2004). Equity in higher education. Retrieved 25 February 2005 from http://www.dest.gov.au/highered/equity.htm. Department of Education, Training & Youth Affairs. (1999a). Equity in higher education. Occasional Paper Series, 99-A. Canberra: Commonwealth of Australia. Final and authorised version first published in the Australian Journal of Career Development in  Volume 14, number 2, published by the Australian Council for Educational Research.  Copyright © 2005 Australian Council for Educational Research. Department of Education, Training and Youth Affairs (DETYA) (1999b). Higher education equity plans for the 1999-2001 triennium. Higher Education Division. Canberra: Author. Department of Education, Training and Youth Affairs (DETYA) (1999c). Higher education indigenous education strategies 1999-2001. Higher Education Division. Canberra: Author Ford, T., & McIlveen, P. (2003). Family guide to USQ. [Brochure]. Toowoomba: University of Southern Queensland. Hansen, S. S. (2003). Career counsellors as advocates and change agents for equality. Career Development Quarterly, 52, 43-53. Hartung, P. J., & Blustein, D. L. (2002). Reason, intuition, and social justice: Elaborating on Parsons’s career decision-making model. Journal of Counseling and Development, 80, 41-47. Herr, E. L. (2003). The future of career counselling as an instrument of public policy. Career Development Quarterly, 52, 8-17. Herr, E. L., Cramer, S. H., & Niles, S. G. (2004). Career guidance and counselling through the lifespan. Systematic approaches. 6th ed. Boston: Pearson. Hughes, C. (1995). Career education and educating for social justice. Australian Journal of Career Development, 4, 12-14. International Association for Educational and Vocational Guidance. (2001). The Paris 2001 IAEVG Declaration on Educational and Vocational Guidance. Retrieved 10 September 2004 from http://www.iaevg.org/iaevg/nav.cfm?lang=2&menu=1&submenu=1. Final and authorised version first published in the Australian Journal of Career Development in  Volume 14, number 2, published by the Australian Council for Educational Research.  Copyright © 2005 Australian Council for Educational Research. Long, M., & Hayden, M. (2001). Paying their way. A survey of Australian undergraduate university student finances, 2000. Canberra: Australian Vice- Chancellors’ Committee. Martin, L. M. (1994). Equity and General Performance Indicators in Higher Education: Volume 1. Equity Indicators. Canberra: Australian Government Publishing Service. McIlveen, P., Cameron, M., McLachlan, D. & Gunn, J. (in press). The study-to-work transition of university students with a disability. Australian Journal of Rehabilitation Counselling. McIlveen, P. Ford, T., & Everton, B. (in press). Facilitating transition from rural schools to university. Australian Journal of Career Development. National Board of Employment Education and Training. (1994). Resource implications of the introduction of good strategies in higher education for disadvantaged students. Commissioned report No. 30. Canberra: Australian Government Publishing Service. Nelson, B. (2002). Higher education at the crossroads. Ministerial discussion paper. Canberra: Commonwealth of Australia. O’Brien, K. M. (2001). The legacy of Parsons: Career counsellors and vocational psychologists as agents of social change. Career Development Quarterly, 50, 66-76. Patton, W., & McMahon, M. (1997). The systems theory framework. In W. Patton & M. McMahon (Eds.), Career development in practice. A systems theory perspective (pp. 15-34). Sydney: New Hobsons Press. Patton, W., & McMahon, M. (1999). Career development and systems theory. A new relationship. Pacific Grove, CA: Brooks/Cole Publishing Company. Final and authorised version first published in the Australian Journal of Career Development in  Volume 14, number 2, published by the Australian Council for Educational Research.  Copyright © 2005 Australian Council for Educational Research. Sarra, C. (1997). Systems theory and the aboriginal career decision maker. In W. Patton & M. McMahon (Eds.), Career development in practice. A systems theory perspective (pp. 47-57). Sydney: New Hobsons Press. Senate Standing Committee on Employment, Education and Training. (1990). Priorities for reform in higher education. Canberra: Australian Government Publishing Service. Taylor, R. (1977). Career development, socio-economic disadvantage and participation in higher education. In W. Patton & M. McMahon (Eds.), Career development in practice. A systems theory perspective (pp. 59-70). Sydney: New Hobsons Press. Tinto, V. (1998). Colleges as communities: Taking research on student persistence seriously. The Review of Higher Education, 21, 167-177. United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organisation. (1998). Handbook on career counselling. A practical manual for developing, implementing and assessing career counselling services in higher education settings. Paris: Author. Williams, T., Long, M., Carpenter, P., & Hayden, M. (1993). Entering higher education in the 1980s. Evaluations and Investigations Program. Department of Employment, Education and Training. Canberra: Australian Government Publishing Service. Final and authorised version first published in the Australian Journal of Career Development in  Volume 14, number 2, published by the Australian Council for Educational Research.  Copyright © 2005 Australian Council for Educational Research. AUTHORS Peter McIlveen is a psychologist and Manager of the Careers Employment & Welfare unit at the USQ. Bradley Everton is the Psychologist, Careers and Equity at the USQ and has a brief to provide career counselling and education services to empower students from identified equity groups. John Clarke is Manager Planning & Quality and Executive Officer to the Vice- Chancellor at USQ. He has wide experience in equity research and policy development in the Australian higher education sector. Final and authorised version first published in the Australian Journal of Career Development in  Volume 14, number 2, published by the Australian Council for Educational Research.  Copyright © 2005 Australian Council for Educational Research. THEORY AND PRACTICE Why is Systems Theory Framework relevant to the issues of career development and social justice? Answer - The STF embeds the individual’s career development within broad social, economic and environmental factors and thus induces consideration of variables that impact upon a person’s position and resources within society. What are some of the main equity groups that require the attention of career practitioner working within Australian universities? Answer - Indigenous students; women studying in non-traditional areas; students with a disability; students from a rural or isolated region; students from language backgrounds other than English; and students from low socio-economic status backgrounds Which Commonwealth Department provides a valuable website containing information on equity resources? Answer – Department of Education, Science and Training. work_bwolw7wnynbeddmrtzz743mmcq ---- http://csp.sagepub.com/ Critical Social Policy http://csp.sagepub.com/content/31/2/241 The online version of this article can be found at: DOI: 10.1177/0261018310396032 2011 31: 241 originally published online 9 February 2011Critical Social Policy Karen Bell Environmental justice in Cuba Published by: http://www.sagepublications.com can be found at:Critical Social PolicyAdditional services and information for http://csp.sagepub.com/cgi/alertsEmail Alerts: http://csp.sagepub.com/subscriptionsSubscriptions: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navReprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navPermissions: http://csp.sagepub.com/content/31/2/241.refs.htmlCitations: What is This? - Feb 9, 2011 OnlineFirst Version of Record - Apr 13, 2011Version of Record >> at EASTERN MICHIGAN UNIV on February 28, 2013csp.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://csp.sagepub.com/ http://csp.sagepub.com/content/31/2/241 http://www.sagepublications.com http://csp.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts http://csp.sagepub.com/subscriptions http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav http://csp.sagepub.com/content/31/2/241.refs.html http://csp.sagepub.com/content/31/2/241.full.pdf http://csp.sagepub.com/content/early/2011/02/08/0261018310396032.full.pdf http://online.sagepub.com/site/sphelp/vorhelp.xhtml http://csp.sagepub.com/ 241 © The Author(s), 2011. Reprints and permissions: http://www.sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav Critical Social Policy, 0261-0183 101; Vol. 31(2): 241–265; 396032 10.1177/0261018310396032 http://csp.sagepub.com  K A R E N B E L L University of Bristol Environmental justice in Cuba Abstract ‘Environmental justice’ refers to the human right to a healthy and safe environment, a fair share of natural resources, access to environmental information and participation in environmental decision-making. Some analysts have argued that environmental justice is undermined by the political economy of capitalism. This paper builds on this analysis by evaluating the environmental justice situation in Cuba, a country where there is little capitalist influence. Evidence is based on participant obser- vation and interviews in Cuba, as well as secondary quantitative data. The research findings suggest that Cuba fares relatively well in terms of environmental justice, but still faces a number of challenges regarding the quality of its environment and some aspects of the environmental decision-making process. However, many of its ongoing problems can be attributed to global capitalist pressures. Key words: capitalism, causes, environment, equality, participation Most commentators agree that the term ‘environmental justice’ emerged in the 1980s, out of resistance to the siting of toxic facilities in black and other minority ethnic communities in the United States. A defining moment was the publication of research that showed that hazardous installations, such as toxic waste dumps, were often located in areas with higher percentages of ‘people of color’ (UCC, 1987). This study was followed by further investigations which confirmed that poor and minority ethnic communities in the US were dispropor- tionately exposed to environmental hazards (Bryant and Mohai, 1992; Adeola, 1994; Cutter, 1995) and received unequal protection under environmental law (Lavelle and Coyle, 1992). Thus, the term was originally applied to the socio-spatial distribution of pollution within national borders and, in particular, environmental racism in facility at EASTERN MICHIGAN UNIV on February 28, 2013csp.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://csp.sagepub.com/ 242 C R I T I C A L S O C I A L P O L I C Y 3 1 ( 2 ) siting. However, influenced by social movement discourse and recent literature (e.g. Pellow, 2007; Schlosberg, 2007), I am using the term in a broader and more radical way to include the overall quality of the environment (substantive environmental justice); the extent of envi- ronmental equalities (distributive environmental justice); and the fair- ness and inclusiveness of environmental decision-making (procedural environmental justice).1 At the same time, I am limiting the discussion to the current intra-national situation, rather than the inter-national or inter-generational dimensions. Policy responses to environmental injustice, in both the US and the UK, seem to have made little, if any, difference to the problem (Sustainable Development Commission, 2003; Bullard et al., 2007). It is unlikely that the issue can be solved until the causes are better understood, yet there has been relatively little academic attention given to researching the underlying factors (Walker and Eames, 2006). Debates about causes have tended to be around the following themes: discrimination (Bullard, 1983, 1994; Center, 1996; PinderHughes, 1996; Bullard et al., 2007); market efficiency (Been, 1994; Lambert and Boerner, 1997); industrialization (Beck, 1992, 1995, 1999; Schnaiberg and Gould, 2000); power inequalities (Boyce, 2001; Pastor et al., 2001; Berry, 2003); and the political economy of capitalism (Faber and O’Conner, 1993; Harvey, 1996; Pellow, 2007). The aim of this study was to build on this debate by focussing on the last, and most frequently overlooked of these, the political econ- omy of capitalism. The few authors that do explicitly focus on capital- ism allege that it fosters environmental injustice through producing intense ecological harm, as well as extensive social hierarchies, primar- ily those of race, class, gender and nation. This occurs, they maintain, as a direct result of capitalism’s need for infinite economic growth, requiring incessant production and consumption. These consumption patterns can only be maintained through appropriation and destruc- tion of the resources of the poorer nations and communities. In addi- tion, under capitalism, there is a need for short-term profit, in order for businesses to survive. This encourages cost cutting, putting pressure on corporations to choose the cheapest, rather than the most sustainable, process so that there is a clear and direct conflict between environmen- tal protection and corporate profits. Such economic ‘efficiency’ also cre- ates social inequality by depressing wages and fostering unemployment whilst, at the same time, profits accrue to shareholders. Inequality is further reinforced as benefits are distributed according to purchasing at EASTERN MICHIGAN UNIV on February 28, 2013csp.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://csp.sagepub.com/ B E L L — E N V I R O N M E N T A L J U S T I C E I N C U B A 243 power. Thus, it is claimed ‘The production of social inequalities by race, class, gender, and nation is not an aberration or the result of mar- ket failures. Rather, it is evidence of the normal, routine, functioning of capitalist economies’ (Pellow, 2007: 17). In order to contribute to this debate, it seemed useful to actually look at a non-capitalist state to see how it fares in terms of environ- mental justice (in its widest sense). Thus, I decided to look at a coun- try which, after 50 years of socialism, I believed would be minimally impacted by capitalism – Cuba. The country was also of particular interest as it had recently been identified as the only country in the world to have achieved sustainable development by the World Wildlife Fund (2006). Methodology Evaluating Cuba’s performance in terms of environmental justice was challenging as it was hindered by the extreme positions that most com- mentators seem to take.2 This is the result of the political context in which Cuba exists. Since the revolution in 1959, Cuba has been the recipient of relentless US efforts to overthrow the government. As well as an ongoing blockade,3 this has included proactive sponsorship of opposition groups; stated attempts to use academic work to destabi- lize the Cuban system; a crusade of disinformation; and a campaign of aggression, including sabotage, terrorism, an invasion, attempted assassinations of the leadership, biological attacks and hotel bombings (Saney, 2004; Kapcia, 2008). The situation amounts to an undeclared war and, consequently, many Cubans are reluctant to admit any failings which could be used as justification for further attacks. Thus, any claim of objectivity or neutrality when researching Cuba appears nonsensical since, whatever is said about the country, can be used as ammunition by one side or the other. To increase reliability, therefore, I employed a complex range of data gathering techniques including participant observations, docu- mentary analysis, literature reviews, semi-structured interviews and secondary quantitative material. The fieldwork took place over 15 weeks, between mid December, 2008, and the end of March, 2009. I was based in Havana but also trav- elled fairly extensively, visiting 19 other towns, cities and villages on the island. I interviewed a total of 68 people: those representing state at EASTERN MICHIGAN UNIV on February 28, 2013csp.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://csp.sagepub.com/ 244 C R I T I C A L S O C I A L P O L I C Y 3 1 ( 2 ) institutions (n = 21); those representing civil society organizations (n = 17); experts (n = 5); workers (n = 9); and residents (n = 16). Participant observation involved visiting areas, projects and commu- nities where there were potential environmental justice issues; taking part in activities that constitute the everyday lives of the people expe- riencing the environmental justice or injustice; and attending public meetings where environmental decisions were being made. The study was necessarily exploratory, as there do not appear to have been any previous studies specifically looking at environmental justice within Cuba. It was, therefore, broad in scope, so it is only possible to highlight some of the main findings here. These will be discussed with regard to substantive, distributional and procedural environmental justice. Substantive environmental justice in Cuba Historically, Cuba has suffered hundreds of years of environmental degradation as a result of intensive exploitation of minerals and other natural resources, lack of environmental legislation, exhaustive export commodity production, and poor agricultural practices (see Diaz- Briquets and Pérez-López, 2000; Houck, 2003; Maldonado, 2003; Whittle and Rey Santos, 2006). These problems seem to have begun under colonial rule, first by Spain and then by the United States, dur- ing which time the main concern was exploitation of natural resources (Fernández, 2002; Funes Monzote, 2008). Even after the 1959 revolu- tion, the degradation intensified when the country embraced the so- called ‘green revolution’, an era of intensive, industrialized agriculture and heavy use of chemical fertilizers and pesticides4 (Gonzalez, 2003). However, in 1992, after a landmark speech at the Rio Earth Sum- mit, the government initiated a series of reforms aimed at redressing past environmental harms and minimizing future degradation. This included establishing a new and powerful Ministry of Science, Technol- ogy, and Environment (CITMA); publishing the country’s first envi- ronmental programme – ‘The National Environmental Strategy’; and passing new framework environmental legislation, Law 81, ‘The Law of the Environment’. The new law established the basis of an enforce- ment system that includes emissions monitoring, inspections, civil and criminal penalties, as well as opportunities for private citizens to seek at EASTERN MICHIGAN UNIV on February 28, 2013csp.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://csp.sagepub.com/ B E L L — E N V I R O N M E N T A L J U S T I C E I N C U B A 245 justice regarding environmental violations through the courts. The most important general principles of Law 81, from an environmental justice perspective, are that it establishes: � the right to a healthy environment (Article 4(a)) � the precautionary principle5 � the right to environmental information (Article 4(e)) � the right to be consulted on environmental actions and decisions (Article 4(k)) � the necessity for community participation to achieve effective environ- mental decision-making (Article 4(m)) � the right to access to administrative and judicial bodies to demand com- pliance with the law (Article 4(l)). These legislative reforms were accompanied by practical measures which made a dramatic difference to Cuban daily life. For example, industrialized agriculture, featuring large-scale irrigation schemes and considerable inputs of chemicals, was rejected in favour of organic food production (Rosset and Benjamin, 1995; Levins, 2005). Cuba also moved away from a transportation system that was dependent on oil (Diaz-Briquets and Perez-Lopez, 1995) and turned to renewable energy sources and energy conservation (see Guevara-Stone, 2009). In addition, reforestation schemes were stepped up and systems were established to ensure managed protection of ecologically, socially, historically, and culturally important areas. It is frequently alleged (e.g. Kaufman, 1993; Diaz-Briquets and Perez-Lopez, 1993) that the environmental improvements made in the 1990s were not born of any genuine environmental commitment on the part of the government, but were rather an improvised emergency response to the ‘Special Period’. However, I do not believe this to be the case as Cuba could have chosen other options, such as IMF-style cuts to basic services, in response to the crisis. Moreover, the environmental changes were consistent with ongoing developments and debates in the country. For example, there were a number of environmental pro- grammes already in place, going back to the 1960s (Levins, 2005), and the pre-existing environmental law (Law 33, passed in 1981) had been widely considered to be pioneering for the region (Whittle and Rey Santos, 2006). The relative weight accorded to environmental concerns in Cuba in the first decades after the revolution, reflected the dominant thinking globally, though there were fierce debates between ecologists at EASTERN MICHIGAN UNIV on February 28, 2013csp.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://csp.sagepub.com/ 246 C R I T I C A L S O C I A L P O L I C Y 3 1 ( 2 ) and those who advocated ‘modernization’ (Levins, 2005). Levins argues that it is socialism that enabled the ecologists to win the debate in Cuba because ‘Nobody was pushing pesticides or mechanization to make a profit . . . Socialism made ecological choices more likely’ (2005: 14). Consequently, many people that I interviewed, or spoke to infor- mally, in Cuba said they were happy with their environment and proud of the country’s achievements in this respect. The most widely appreciated aspects included the provision of low-cost (or, sometimes, free) housing, food, public transport and utilities; successful energy efficiency programmes; care of the population during hurricanes;6 urban agriculture initiatives;7 improvement of public transport; and improvements in workplace safety. The ‘Revolución Energética’ (Energy Revolution), which began in 2006, is a particularly good example of an environmental policy, which also addresses environ- mental justice. This initiative endeavoured to save energy and use more sustainable sources. The programme included replacing house- hold appliances with more efficient and safer equipment, supplied free or at low cost to the entire population. Cuba’s transport policy is another example of a strategy which both improves the environ- ment and increases social justice. The number of private cars has been kept in check by the state’s car ownership policy where people cannot purchase cars just because they have the money to buy them. All cars are assigned according to the needs and responsibility that the person has and there is no encouragement to perceive cars as an individual item for consumption. There is now considerable investment in pub- lic transport (Taylor, 2009) and, in addition, planning policies have reduced the need for travel. Mixed-use developments are encouraged so that, where new housing is constructed, enough new facilities and jobs are provided locally. Furthermore, financial support enables people to exchange their job for one closer to their home, if they wish (Enoch et al., 2004; Taylor, 2009). However, as well as praising the successes and improvements, many people complained about certain aspects of the environment. These were in regard to inadequate sanitation; shortcomings in the water supply; river and air pollution; deficiencies in waste collection services; dam- aged streets; and inadequate and insufficient housing. This fits with a previous government survey that showed extensive soil erosion, defor- estation, inland and coastal water pollution, loss of biodiversity, and poor sanitation in cities and rural areas (CITMA, 1997). The ‘Special Period’ also increased some problems, including deforestation, illegal at EASTERN MICHIGAN UNIV on February 28, 2013csp.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://csp.sagepub.com/ B E L L — E N V I R O N M E N T A L J U S T I C E I N C U B A 247 hunting and fishing, the trade in wild species, habitat destruction and illegal dumping (CITMA, 1992, cited in Maal-Bared, 2006). Though some of this environmental harm has been committed by individuals, the most severe environmental destruction has resulted from major projects and industries owned by the state or international companies (Maal-Bared, 2006). This has usually been in relation to tourism and industrial production, in particular, there has been a report of serious pollution from the expanding nickel industry8 (Chavez, 2008). The environmental experts I spoke to in Cuba recognized that there was no cause for complacency and were keenly aware of the work to be done (e.g. interviews, Director of Environmental Policy, CITMA; Director of Centre for Environmental Studies, University of Havana). Although there were clearly serious problems in particular areas, if we compare Cuba with other countries, however, it does seem to be doing relatively well in terms of substantial environmental justice. As Table 1 shows, Cuba uses much less energy and emits less CO 2 and other air particulates than the average Latin American country or country of a similar income bracket. In addition, it has much better sanitation coverage than these countries and a similar level of improved water source coverage. So, though substantive environmental justice in Cuba was unsatisfactory, and even seriously deficient for some people, it seems to be comparatively good. Moreover, Cuba has to live with its own pollution because, unlike the developed capitalist countries, it is not exporting its waste to other parts of the world (see Pellow, 2007; Davis and Caldeira, 2010). Distributional environmental justice Cuba puts great emphasis on achieving social equality, and uses macro- economic and social policies based on universality and equitable access to achieve this (Rodríguez and Carrizo Moreno, 1987; Regueiro and Alonso, 2001, cited in Coyula and Hamberg, 2003). This includes measures to reduce wage inequality; keep prices for goods and services low; assure equal and affordable access to essential food and consumer goods through the ‘libreta’ ration system; and extend social security, welfare, sports and cultural activities to the entire population for free, or at very low cost. The introduction of these measures, in particular, the libreta (ration book) had the greatest benefit for the poor, while limiting the excesses of the rich, to some extent. at EASTERN MICHIGAN UNIV on February 28, 2013csp.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://csp.sagepub.com/ 248 C R I T I C A L S O C I A L P O L I C Y 3 1 ( 2 ) However, inequality began to increase in the 1990s as a result of measures brought in to survive an economic crisis (Hamilton, 2002; Uriarte-Gaston, 2004; Mesa-Lago, 2006; Blue, 2007; Morris, 2008). The blockade had pushed Cuba towards an economic dependency on the Soviet Union and the Eastern European ‘Community for Eco- nomic Cooperation’ (COMECON). Consequently, after COMECON collapsed in 1989 and the US blockade tightened, the country faced an economic disaster, with its GDP falling by more than 48% (Diaz- Briquets and Perez-Lopez, 1995). In Cuba, this era was referred to as the ‘Special Period in Peacetime’, implying the need for measures Table 1 Comparison of environmental indicators Indicator Cuba Other UMICs* Other LACs** Energy use (kg of oil equivalent per capita) 944 2109 1243 Electric power consumption (kWh per capita) 1231 2957 1812 Electricity production from coal sources (% of total) 0.0 26.4 5.2 CO 2 emissions (metric tons per capita) 2.2 5.1 2.5 PM10, country level (micrograms per cubic meter)† 17 32 35 Improved water source (% of population with access) 91 94 91 Improved water source, rural (% of rural pop. with access) 78 82 73 Improved water source, urban (% of urban pop. with access) 95 98 97 Improved sanitation facilities (% of pop. with access) 98 82 78 Improved sanitation facilities, rural (% of rural population) 95 63 51 Improved sanitation facilities, urban (% of urban population) 99 89 86 *UMIC = Upper Middle Income Country; **LAC = Latin American Country. †Particulate matter concentrations refer to fine suspended particulates less than 10 microns in diameter (PM10) that are capable of penetrating deep into the respiratory tract and causing significant health damage. The estimates represent the average annual exposure level of the average urban resident (Pandey et al., 2006). Source: World Bank (2009) using most recent data (mainly 2007). at EASTERN MICHIGAN UNIV on February 28, 2013csp.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://csp.sagepub.com/ B E L L — E N V I R O N M E N T A L J U S T I C E I N C U B A 249 that would normally apply in wartime, in order to cushion the effect of the crisis on the population. A high standard of free universal health care and education was maintained (Barbeira et al., 2004) and social programmes to sustain public welfare were stepped up. However, because of its history of colonialism, Cuba was depend- ent on external trade and, therefore, needed to pursue hard currency in order to interact with the capitalist world. Following extensive consultation with the population, this led to the use of market-based policies which some have called concessions to capitalism or an attempt to ‘use capitalism to save socialism’ (Taylor, 2009: 4). These poli- cies included the development of tourism, legalization of the dol- lar, individual self-employment, joint ventures with foreign capital, intensifying exploitation of natural resources for export (especially nickel), and increasing the availability and promotion of consumer goods in order to capture dollars sent as remittances (Dello Buono, 1995; Mesa-Lago, 2005; Raby, 2006). In this context, inequality emerged between those who had access to dollars and those who did not, as well as between those who were employed in the informal sector and those who worked in the formal economy (Morris, 2008). The dollar-based sector of the economy cov- ers the tourist sector, foreign businesses in joint ventures, and some state enterprises that work in export markets (Hamilton, 2002). As in many countries, some of the variation in income inequality has a racial dimension (Blue, 2007). For example, the increase in self-employ- ment, implying access to resources that can be drawn on for the initial investment, discriminated against black people who were less likely to have relatives abroad able to supply these start-up funds (Blue, 2007). However, although income inequality increased, once the value of sub- sidized housing, utilities and food, as well as free services, is factored in, the actual inequalities are much lower. Distributional environmental injustice is built upon not only social inequality, but also residential segregation. In capitalist coun- tries, social-spatial segregation by race and class has been identified as a major factor contributing to environmental injustice (Bullard, 1995; Pulido, 1996; Martinez-Alier, 2003). The classic pattern of spatial segregation also existed in Cuba before the revolution, but most analysts consider that this has been greatly alleviated by the general programmes designed to reduce poverty, as outlined above, as well as a number of specific housing laws and policies (Coyula and Hamberg, 2003; Oliveras and, Núñez, 2004; Ramirez, 2005; Sawyer, at EASTERN MICHIGAN UNIV on February 28, 2013csp.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://csp.sagepub.com/ 250 C R I T I C A L S O C I A L P O L I C Y 3 1 ( 2 ) 2006; Taylor, 2009). These included the Law of Low Rents (1959) and the Law of Urban Reform (1960) which made housing affordable (or free) in any area of the city or country; as well as the redistribution of housing vacated by the wealthy who fled to the US (Taylor, 2009). Most importantly, the lack of a legal land or housing market, whilst allowing mobility through housing ‘swaps’, has largely prevented segregation according to income (Coyula and Hamberg, 2003). However, as Oliveras and, Núñez point out, though these policies have significantly mitigated against segregation, ‘four decades have proven insufficient’ to completely revert a 400 year old development pattern (2004: 21). Thus, although there are no areas officially recog- nized as poor,9 there are some districts where the population, though heterogeneous, is more likely to contain people on lower incomes (Ramirez, 2005). Even so, my fieldwork impressions were that there seemed to be a distinct lack of the separate communities based on income level, social status or race, that are so easily recognizable in capitalist countries. However, it was not possible to verify these findings quantitatively as socio-spatial data at a micro-level are not currently published in Cuba. At a provincial level, some difference in incomes can be seen between Cuba’s provinces, with the eastern provinces worse off than the west (ONE, 2008). Some of this difference seems to be a result of tourism, which is more developed in the western provinces, particularly Havana, allowing greater opportunities for these residents to acquire dollars (Mesa-Lago, 2002; Oliveras and Núñez, 2004). Distributional environmental injustice is built on inequality and social segregation, but defined by unequal access to healthy and safe environments. There was no qualitative evidence from this study of variations in environmental quality according to social category i.e. this was not a problem that I perceived or that was identified by inter- viewees. In terms of the quantitative evidence, the results were contra- dictory. When average provincial income levels were compared with variations in sanitation coverage, river pollution, and per-capita gov- ernmental spending on the environment, there was no apparent rela- tionship between lower income and a poorer environment. However, there did seem to be a weak relationship between low income and a lack of access to improved water supply. Thus, though there was evidence of social inequalities and a mini- mal level of segregation, according to income, there was very little evi- dence of a pattern of distributive environmental justice in Cuba. at EASTERN MICHIGAN UNIV on February 28, 2013csp.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://csp.sagepub.com/ B E L L — E N V I R O N M E N T A L J U S T I C E I N C U B A 251 Procedural environmental justice in Cuba The final aspect of environmental justice to be discussed here is ‘pro- cedural environmental justice’. There is no accepted definition of this term, but in its widest sense, it can be said to include open, honest and inclusive environmental decision-making processes; consistent appli- cation of rules; access to environmental information; and control over environmental justice outcomes (see Bell, 2011). In the West, Cuba is generally portrayed as having few, if any, of these ingredients of procedural justice. It is alleged that there is mini- mal freedom of expression, access to information, democracy, or influ- ence over decision-making of any kind. The most recent Economist Intelligence Unit democracy index, for example, places Cuba 125th out of 144 countries (2008). Also, a recent report states that, in Cuba, people cannot collaborate with each other in a meaningful way against authorities because it would be dangerous and so complaints are limited to what is deemed to be ‘acceptable to the party, the establishment and the institutions of communism in Cuba’ (Freedom House, 2008: 9). However, many Cuba analysts contend that, though the country does not correspond to the capitalist brand of democracy, character- ized by multi-party elections, it exhibits an alternative model based on direct popular democracy, participatory decision-making, election of representative delegates, a vibrant civil society, accountable govern- ment, an emphasis on equality and a willingness to respond to demands for change (see, for example, Cole, 1998; Roman, 2003; Saney, 2004; Raby, 2006; Kapcia, 2008; Yaffe, 2009). There is not the space to debate these two vastly different views of Cuban society here, so I will focus only on the aspects of democracy that directly relate to environmental matters. There is a vast network of institutions and organizations that play a part in influencing environ- mental decisions in Cuba. As well as the legislative and executive bodies of government, the judiciary, the mass organizations, the Communist Party and environmental activist organizations, all participate. Pro- posals for serious reforms of general government policy are circulated widely and discussed extensively in local branches of mass organizations, schools, workplaces and universities, before being put to referendum or opinion channelled into National Assembly debates (Cole, 1998; Raby, 2006). The key to understanding the Cuban concept of democracy is the ‘mandat imperatif’ (or the ‘instructed delegate model’) as developed by Rousseau and the Paris Commune. In Cuba this is organized through at EASTERN MICHIGAN UNIV on February 28, 2013csp.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://csp.sagepub.com/ 252 C R I T I C A L S O C I A L P O L I C Y 3 1 ( 2 ) the system of Poder Popular (Popular Power). The central idea is that representatives should be truly accountable and responsive to their con- stituents, attempting to resolve all matters presented to them. When I asked people how they would try to change an environmental situation or make a complaint about the environment, they almost always said that they would do this by approaching their Poder Popular delegate. They generally had great faith in their delegate as a representative, find- ing them to be reliable, hard-working and trustworthy. This confidence may be a result of the accountability of the system, in that an ineffective delegate would quickly lose their job, as explained here: We meet with those that choose us four times a year. People are very demanding at these meetings. They can revoke us at any moment, and they do. We are not sacked by the National Assembly or anyone else, but by the people who elect us. They can do it whenever they want. They can say he’s not what we thought, we made a mistake and that’s it. (interview, Delegate, Poder Popular, Habana del Este) Thus, people generally felt that they had been able to make their opin- ion known about environmental concerns, though the matter was not necessarily resolved in their favour, especially if additional resources were required. Contrary to those who claim that workers in Cuba are not free to make demands because there is no ‘right to strike’, there is, in fact, no legislation covering strikes, to prohibit or allow them (Ludlam, 2009), though trade unions can close down the workplace if the conditions are such that an imminent workplace accident is fore- seen. Workers and union officials have exercised this right, for exam- ple, where there was not the necessary protective equipment (interview, Head of Social Labour, National Trade Union Council (CTC)). However, there are some limitations on the forms of resistance that Cubans are prepared to utilize. Street protest, for example, though not illegal, is not seen as an effective strategy, as explained by an environ- mental campaigner: It will not be efficient [to protest] and it can be manipulated by dis- sidents and outside sources, because there is a huge magnifying glass on Cuba and it can be misinterpreted . . . For us, it does not make sense to chain yourselves to trees and things like that . . . (interview, Environ- mental Educator, Antonio Nuñez Jímenez Foundation for Nature and Humanity (FANJ)) at EASTERN MICHIGAN UNIV on February 28, 2013csp.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://csp.sagepub.com/ B E L L — E N V I R O N M E N T A L J U S T I C E I N C U B A 253 In terms of access to information, according to the informal conversa- tions and interviews I carried out, people in Cuba had a number of ways that they found out about their local environment: through Poder Popular, the media, the mass organizations, informal contacts, CITMA, other relevant ministries, health and safety representatives at work, the internet, the library and even their local GPs.10 Though some envi- ronmental information is published in Cuba, the more detailed and specific information was not readily available, however. Even so, infor- mation could be obtained upon request, as indicated by this comment from an environmental activist: There are many factories upstream and a lot of the pollution from them goes into the rivers that pass through the protected area . . . In our pro- posal [to make improvements to the protected area] we have listed all the names of the pollutants . . . CITMA passed this information to us . . . they gave us all the information and also the permission to use the information in the presentations . . . The only thing that we really have in abundance in Cuba is knowledge. We don’t hide what we know, nor do the institu- tions. (interview, Representative, Abra del Rio, Environmental Project, Cojimar) In terms of control over outcomes, the fieldwork interviews and con- versations revealed numerous situations which demonstrated that the environmental decision-making processes worked well for citizens. For example, I was told about reductions in the amount of polluting emis- sions from production plants as a result of citizen or worker complaints in Guanabo, Matanzas, the Bay of Havana and Holguín (interviews, Protected Area Team, Habana del Este; Coordinator of the Network of Political Ecology in Latin America and the Caribbean; Director of Social Work, Holguín). I was also given examples of development proposals which had been abandoned or relocated as a result of public pressure, for example a dam in Baracoa (interview, Resident, Baracoa), and a micro-generator in Regla, Havana (interview, Coordinator of the Network of Political Ecology in Latin America and the Caribbean). However, there was also contradictory evidence, with numerous examples of a lack of citizen power. For example, leaking water pipes which had not been fixed despite local people complaining for more than 30 years (interview, Resident, San Miguel del Padrón); ongoing air pollution from a local hospital (interview, Resident, Cayo Hueso, Centro Habana); and oil exploration projects begun without prior at EASTERN MICHIGAN UNIV on February 28, 2013csp.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://csp.sagepub.com/ 254 C R I T I C A L S O C I A L P O L I C Y 3 1 ( 2 ) consultation (interview, Protected Area Team, Habana del Este). I was also told that the compulsory requirements to organize public hearings and other consultations were sometimes bypassed. An environmental NGO worker, for instance, said: When the electrical generation was decentralised all over the country, they tried to proceed very, very fast and sometimes they did not follow the protocol with the environmental impact assessment and the licence . . . It can be when there is an interest of the central Government things happen very fast and sometimes they push and jump some of the stages. Then after, when the problem happens, they realise they have to be cor- rective because they didn’t think enough of the environmental conse- quences. (interview, Environmental Educator, Antonio Nuñez Jímenez Foundation for Nature and Humanity (FANJ)) Another example of this concerns transgenic production. Despite the government commitment to the precautionary principle, GMOs (genetically modified organisms) have recently been released into the atmosphere for the first time in Cuba, without public consultation. In April 2010, scientists at the Center for Genetic Engineering and Biotechnology (CIGB) began ‘field tests’ with a corn transgenic. Field tests are probably an irreversible step because of the danger of cross-contamination through pollen drift11 and, therefore, not to be undertaken lightly. Agro-ecologists in Cuba are now opposing the cultivation of this crop and asking for a moratorium until there has been a public debate on the issue (interview, Agro-Ecologist, University of Matanzas). Thus, procedural environmental justice in Cuba was strong in terms of the network of organizations involved, the legislation and the participatory culture, but there were some deficiencies in terms of discouragement of protest, a lack of easily available information and inconsistencies, or omissions, with regard to consultation processes. Causes of environmental injustice in Cuba A number of factors seem to explain Cuba’s current environmental justice problems. To begin with, colonialism in Cuba permanently altered the island economically, environmentally and socially, orientat- ing the country toward primary export production, stifling indigenous at EASTERN MICHIGAN UNIV on February 28, 2013csp.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://csp.sagepub.com/ B E L L — E N V I R O N M E N T A L J U S T I C E I N C U B A 255 industry and tying Cuba to a dependency on external trade (Fernández, 2002; Funes Monzote, 2008; Kapcia, 2008).12 Secondly, the blockade (which could hit hard as a result of this dependency) has affected the country in terms of the availability and cost of technology, as well as a general shortage of resources. For exam- ple, problems with water supply have been linked to a shortage of replacement parts for the distribution network, originally built using US components (American Association for World Health, 1997).13 The resulting lack of resources has also reduced the capacity of CITMA to carry out monitoring, to replace and modify polluting facilities, and to adopt consistent standards, as explained by CITMA’s Director of the Environment: The new industry, since 1990, complies with international standards and norms . . . but the old industries, say, the cement factory in Camaguey, do emit pollution . . . The chimneys are very old . . . If we close the factory it will improve the environment. But the state can’t afford that. They don’t want to close the factory because it is a source of income and because it is the workplace. Every case is particular and there are many factors involved – political, economic, environmental – and they all have to be balanced . . . If you apply strict environmental standards today you would have a list where you would have to close sixty or seventy factories now but if you closed these factories it would be a problem for us. It is complicated. (interview, Director, Directorate of Environmental Policy, CITMA) In addition, the US blockade seems to have conditioned and limited Cuba’s possibilities to achieve procedural justice. Much of the restric- tions can be related to the fact that Cuba has had to operate in an international situation where the dominant world power is intent on its destruction (Lievesley, 2004; Kapcia, 2008). This has given Cuba a sense of siege, and justified a war footing and control of expression and political action (Kapcia, 2008). Kapcia states that it is possible to cor- relate the amount of control with ‘the level of threat posed or perceived’ (Kapcia, 2008: 133), so that moments of greater external pressure are associated with greater expectations for the population to conform. Thirdly, the economic crisis (which would almost certainly not have happened were it not for the context of both the blockade and the history of colonialism) led to the initiation of a number of poli- cies, generally associated with capitalism. These measures, especially tourism, self-employment and the intensive exploitation of natural at EASTERN MICHIGAN UNIV on February 28, 2013csp.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://csp.sagepub.com/ 256 C R I T I C A L S O C I A L P O L I C Y 3 1 ( 2 ) resources, have had a negative influence on Cuba’s environment and society. For example, consumerism has increased as certain foods and experiences enjoyed by tourists have come to symbolize the good life and people come to gain status and identity from material, rather than social, achievements (Taylor, 2009). This may be linked to increased inequality, as there is now mounting evidence that inequality drives higher consumerism (Wilkinson and Pickett, 2009). Conclusion Cuba’s environmental justice successes seemed to be linked to policies based on meeting basic needs, prioritizing equality of outcomes, inno- vative programmes, participatory democracy, re-localizing production and consumption, and sharing more. Thus, the study shows us the importance of a commitment to political and social equality, as well as a healthy environment, in order to achieve environmental justice. The causes of the injustices that occurred in Cuba seemed to be a result of a complex interplay between a range of factors, such as a his- tory of colonialism; a shortage of resources; the economic blockade; US political hostility; development patterns; industrialization; the need to acquire hard currency; as well as management issues and it is important not to be too simplistic about this. However, most of these factors seem to be underpinned by global capitalist pressures, impacting via colo- nialism, the blockade and the need for hard currency. Discrimination, market efficiency, industrialization and power inequalities can also be seen to influence the situation in Cuba, but generally are more problematic as a result of the context of capital- ism. For example, past discrimination against black people enables enduring inequalities in the new private enterprise context and mar- ket ‘efficiency’ means that Cuba intensively extracts nickel as required by global capitalism. Thus, it does seem that, even in Cuba, capital- ism seems to undermine its efforts to achieve social and environmental equality and well-being. This seems to reinforce the idea that capital- ism is a fundamental factor that should not be ignored in any analysis of environmental justice. However, socialism has also been associated with environmental problems. Though socialism has always contained an ecological per- spective (Burkett, 1999; Bellamy Foster, 2000, 2008), some develop- ments in socialist countries have, clearly, also been environmentally at EASTERN MICHIGAN UNIV on February 28, 2013csp.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://csp.sagepub.com/ B E L L — E N V I R O N M E N T A L J U S T I C E I N C U B A 257 damaging. The Soviet Union, for example, succumbed to an extreme version of the productivism, and its associated environmental destruc- tion, that characterized early twentieth-century modernity, in general (Bellamy Foster, 2008). As Cuba’s Director of the Environment empha- sized, any economic system, socialist, or otherwise, needs to be driven by an environmental ethos: It does not mean that, with socialism, the environment automatically improves. For example, what happened in Europe, with the countries of Eastern Europe, there were a thousand disasters. That is to say socialism creates a better opportunity but this opportunity has to be built upon and materialised but I think yes, that socialism is an advantage . . . But I emphasise, it is not automatic, you have to try to create a socialist system where the environmental agenda is driven well, otherwise you will still have environmental problems. Nothing is given, it has to be achieved. (interview, Director, Directorate of Environmental Policy, CITMA) However, the question that is being considered here is, not whether we need socialism, but whether we need an alternative to capitalism. Some argue that new or reformed types of capitalism are, or can be, less environmentally or socially damaging (e.g. Porritt, 2005). These, and several ecological economists and social justice analysts (e.g. Daly and Farley, 2004; Wilkinson and Pickett, 2009), do not urge the demo- lition and rebuilding of the whole economy, but rather advocate the reform and improvement of existing institutions. They propose poli- cies that can be carried out by governments such as improved regula- tion; environmental taxes and subsidies; high and low income limits; and workers’ co-operatives. However, though these policies may help, they may not be enough in themselves, because capitalism depends on economic growth which does not seem to be compatible with a healthy environment. As the Copenhagen Climate Summit in 2009 showed, capitalist economies tend to promote profitable environmental solu- tions such as carbon trading, agro-fuels and nuclear power, all of which will probably be devastating in terms of environmental justice. Thus, Copenhagen’s parallel conference, the ‘Klimaforum’, formulated a peo- ple’s declaration calling for ‘system change – not climate change!’ Whether or not we might wish to emulate some of Cuba’s environ- mental and social policies, the country is a living reminder that there are radically different ways that we could organize our world. As we in the West now struggle with our own ‘Special Period’, it may be time to at EASTERN MICHIGAN UNIV on February 28, 2013csp.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://csp.sagepub.com/ 258 C R I T I C A L S O C I A L P O L I C Y 3 1 ( 2 ) grasp the opportunities inherent in this situation and initiate the kind of radical transformation that will achieve social and environmental justice for all. Notes 1. A study that only considers distributional justice is severely limiting, since it implies that the solution to environmental injustice would be to share environmental burdens evenly (Heiman, 1996; Faber, 1998; Schlosberg, 2004; Walker and Bulkeley, 2006; Stanley, 2009). 2. In particular, the English language literature on Cuba is dominated by ‘Cubanologists’, academics who are engaged in an ideological struggle against Cuba (Rodríguez, 1983). 3. Following other authors, such as Lievesley (2004), I will be using the word ‘blockade’ rather than ‘embargo’ throughout this paper because the US does not just refuse to trade with Cuba but actively intervenes in Cuba’s relations with other countries. The US blockade began in 1963, but was reinforced in 1992 by the ‘Torricelli Law’ and, in 1996, by the ‘Helms-Burton Act’. The 1992 act prohibited foreign-based subsidiaries of US companies from trading with Cuba, travel to Cuba by US citizens, and family remittances to Cuba. Under the 1996 law, any non-US company that deals economically with Cuba can be sub- jected to legal action. The Obama administration has recently eased some of the travel and remittance restrictions on Cuban Americans (see Eckstein, 2009). 4. The projects within the green revolution spread technologies that had already existed, but had not been widely used outside of industrialized nations, including pesticides and synthetic fertilizers. In Cuba, as in much of the world, these practices resulted in extensive water pollution, soil erosion and loss of natural areas (Diaz-Briquets and Perez-Lopez, 1993; Gonzalez, 2003). 5. The Rio Declaration, where a globally accepted definition of the precau- tionary principle was developed, states: ‘. . . the precautionary approach shall be widely applied by States according to their capabilities. Where there are threats of serious or irreversible damage, lack of full scientific certainty shall not be used as a reason for postponing cost-effective mea- sures to prevent environmental degradation’ (UNEP, 1992: Principle 15). 6. Cuba had experienced three devastating hurricanes in 2008, the year pre- ceding my arrival, named Gustav, Ike and Paloma. The government had taken precautionary measures so that there was minimum loss of life. Only 7 people had died, whereas 700 were killed in the neighbouring island of Haiti. at EASTERN MICHIGAN UNIV on February 28, 2013csp.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://csp.sagepub.com/ B E L L — E N V I R O N M E N T A L J U S T I C E I N C U B A 259 7. Many of the mini-dumps in Havana have been cleaned up in the last ten years as a result of the government policy to allow unused land to be leased rent- and tax-free to small farmers on a usufruct basis (interview, Worker, Organopónico, Centro Habana). 8. The Cuban nickel industry surpassed tourism as the country’s top foreign exchange earner in 2007. 9. Poverty is seen to be a structural problem of capitalist societies so that the sector of the population that are living on low incomes in Cuba is usually defined as a ‘. . . population at risk of not being able to meet some basic needs’ (Ferriol Muruaga, 1997: 370). 10. All Cuban GPs are trained in environmental issues and how health is affected by the environment. 11. Once released from the anthers into the atmosphere, pollen grains can travel as far as half a mile with a 15 mph wind in a couple of minutes (Nielsen, 2003). 12. This phenomenon is not unique to Cuba, as colonialism has created much ecological and social damage throughout the South (see, for example, Goldsmith, 1993). 13. Though the trading relationship with COMECON helped with resources and technology, since the loss of these economic partners, Cuba has not been able to replace much of the technology that was supplied through COMECON from the 1960s to the 1980s (interview, 28 January 2009; Dr Allan Pierra-Conde, Director, ISMM). References Adeola, F. (1994) ‘Environmental Hazards, Health, and Racial Inequity in Hazardous Waste Distribution’, Environment and Behavior 26: 99–126. American Association for World Health (1997) ‘The Denial of Food and Med- icine: The Impact of the US Embargo on Health and Nutrition in Cuba’. Barbeira, L., De Souza Briggs, X. and Uriarte, M. (2004) ‘The End of Egali-(2004) ‘The End of Egali-‘The End of Egali- tarianism? Economic Inequality and the Future of Social Policy in Cuba’, in J. I. Domínguez, O. E. Pérez Villanueva and L. Barberia (eds) The Cuban Economy at the Start of the Twenty-First Century. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, David Rockefeller Center for Latin American Studies. Beck, U. (1992) Risk Society: Towards a New Modernity. London: SAGE. Beck, U. (1995) Ecological Politics in an Age of Risk. Cambridge: Polity Press. Beck, U. (1999) World Risk Society. Oxford: Polity Press. Been, V. (1994) ‘Locally Undesirable Land Uses in Minority Neighbourhoods: Disproportionate Siting or Market Dynamics?’, Yale Law Journal 103(6): 1383–422. at EASTERN MICHIGAN UNIV on February 28, 2013csp.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://csp.sagepub.com/ 260 C R I T I C A L S O C I A L P O L I C Y 3 1 ( 2 ) Bellamy Foster, J. (2000) Marx’s Ecology. New York: Monthly Review Press. Bellamy Foster, J. (2008) Ecology and the Transition from Capitalism to Socialism. New York: Monthly Review Press. Bell, K. F. (2011) ‘Environmental Justice: Lessons from Cuba’, PhD thesis, School for Policy Studies, University of Bristol. Berry, G. R. (2003) ‘Organizing Against Multinational Corporate Power in Cancer Alley: The Activist Community as Primary Stakeholder’, Organi- zation and Environment 16(1): 3–33. Blue, S. A. (2007) ‘The Erosion of Racial Equality in the Context of Cuba’s Dual Economy’, Latin American Politics and Society 49(3): 35–68. Boyce, J. K. (2001) ‘Is Inequality Bad for the Environment and Bad for your Health?’ Different Takes 8. Amherst, MA: Population and Development Program at Hampshire College. Bryant, B. and Mohai, P. (eds) (1992) Race and the Incidence of Environmental Hazards: A Time for Discourse. Boulder, CO: Westview Press. Bullard, R. D. (1983) ‘Solid Waste Sites and the Black Houston Community’, Sociological Enquiry 53: 273–88. Bullard, R. D. (1994) Dumping in Dixie: Race, Class and Environmental Quality. Boulder, CO: Westview Press. Bullard, R. D. (1995) ‘Residential Segregation and Urban Quality of Life’, pp. 76–85 in B. Bryant (ed.) Environmental Justice: Issues, Policies and Solu- tions. Washington DC: Island Press. Bullard, R. D., Mohai, P., Saha, R. and Wright, B. (2007) Toxic Wastes and Race at Twenty: 1987–2007. Cleveland, OH: United Church of Christ, Justice and Witness Ministries. Burkett, P. (1999) Marx and Nature. New York: St. Martin’s Press. Center, J. (1996) ‘Waste Management and Risk Assessment: Environmental Discrimination through Regulation’, Urban Geography 17: 400–18. Chavez, J. C. (2008) ‘Nickel Industry Contaminating Cuban Coasts’, El Nuevo Herald 7 August [http://www.minesandcommunities.org/article. php?a=8768]. CITMA (Ministry of Science, Technology, and Environment) (1992) Refer- ring to the negative repercussions of the blockade in the development and environment field. La Habana, Cuba, Academia de Ciencias de Cuba. CITMA (Ministry of Science, Technology, and Environment) (1997) National Environmental Strategy. La Habana, Cuba. Cole, K. (1998) Cuba: From Revolution to Development. London: Pinter. Coyula, M. and Hamberg, J. (2003) ‘The Case of Havana, Cuba’, in Under- standing Slums: Case Studies for the Global Report: 2003. London: Develop- ment Planning Unit, University College London. [http://www.ucl.ac.uk/ dpu-projects/Global_Report/pdfs/Havana.pdf] Cutter, S. (1995) ‘Race, Class and Environmental Justice’, Progress in Human Geography 19: 107–18. at EASTERN MICHIGAN UNIV on February 28, 2013csp.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://csp.sagepub.com/ B E L L — E N V I R O N M E N T A L J U S T I C E I N C U B A 261 Daly, H. E. and Farley, J. (2004) Ecological Economics: Principles and Applica- tions. Washington DC: Island Press. Davis, S. J. and Caldeira, K. (2010) ‘Consumption-based Accounting of CO 2 Emissions’, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America 107(12): 5687–92. Dello Buono, R. A. (1995) ‘An Introduction to Cuba in the Special Period’, in R. A. Dello Buono and J. Bell Lara (eds) Carta Cuba: Lessons from Cuba’s Special Period. Facultad Latino Americana de Ciencias Sociales Programa Cuba, Universidad de La Habana. Diaz-Briquets, S. and Perez-Lopez, J. F. (1993) ‘Water, Development, and Environment in Cuba: A First Look’, Cuba in Transition, vol. 3. Proceed- ings of the Third Annual Meeting of the Association for the Study of the Cuban Economy (ASCE), Florida International University, Miami, 12–14 August. Diaz-Briquets, S. and Perez-Lopez, J. F. (1995) ‘The Special Period and the Environment’, Cuba in Transition, vol. 5. Proceedings of the Fifth Annual Meeting of the Association for the Study of the Cuban Economy (ASCE), University of Miami, 10–12 August. Diaz-Briquets, S. and Perez-Lopez, J. F. (2000) Conquering Nature: The Envi- ronmental Legacy of Socialism in Cuba. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press. Eckstein, S. (2009) ‘The Personal is Political: The Cuban Ethnic Electoral Policy Cycle’, Latin American Politics and Society 51(1): 119–48. Economist Intelligence Unit (2008) ‘Democracy Index 2008’. London: The Economist. Enoch, M., Warren, J. P., Valdés Rios, H. and Menoyo, E. H. (2004) ‘The Effect of Economic Restrictions on Transport Practices in Cuba’, Trans- port Policy 11(1): 67–76. Faber, D. (ed.) (1998) The Struggle for Ecological Democracy: Environmental Justice Movements in the United States. New York: Guilford Press. Faber, D. and O’Conner, J. (1993) ‘Capitalism and the Crisis of Environmen- talism’, pp. 12–25 in R. Hofrichter (ed.) Toxic Struggles: The Theory and Practice of Environmental Justice. Gabriola Island, BC: New Society Pub- lishers. Fernández, S. J. (2002) Encumbered Cuba: Capital Markets and Revolt, 1878– 1895. Gainesville: University Press of Florida. Ferriol Muruaga, A. (1997) ‘Política Social Cubana: Situación y Transforma- ciones’, Temas No. 11 (julio–septiembre). Freedom House (2008) Change in Cuba: How Citizens View their Country’s Future. Special Report. Washington DC: Freedom House. Funes Monzote, R. (2008) From Rainforest to Cane Field in Cuba: An Environ- mental History since 1492. Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press. at EASTERN MICHIGAN UNIV on February 28, 2013csp.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://csp.sagepub.com/ 262 C R I T I C A L S O C I A L P O L I C Y 3 1 ( 2 ) Goldsmith, E. (1993) ‘Development and Colonialism’, Ecoscript No. 35 (June). Gonzalez, C. (2003) ‘Seasons of Resistance: Sustainable Agriculture and Food Security in Cuba’, Tulane Environmental Law Journal 16 (Special Issue): 685–732. Guevara-Stone, L. (2009) ‘La Revolucion Energetica: Cuba’s Energy Revolution’, Renewable Energy World Magazine 12 [http://www.renewableenergyworld. com/rea/news/article/2009/04/la-revolucion-energetica-cubas-energy- revolution]. Hamilton, D. (2002) ‘Whither Cuban Socialism? The Changing Political Econ- omy of the Cuban Revolution’, Latin American Perspectives 29(3): 18–39. Harvey, D. (1996) Justice, Nature and the Geography of Difference. London: Blackwell. Heiman, M. K. (1996) ‘Race, Waste, and Class: New Perspectives on Envi- ronmental Justice’, Antipode 28(2): 111–21. Houck, O. A. (2003) ‘Thinking about Tomorrow: Cuba’s “Alternative Model” for Sustainable Development’, Tulane Environmental Law Journal 16: 521–32. Kapcia, A. (2008) Cuba in Revolution: A History since the Fifties. London: Reak- tion Books. Kaufman, H. (1993) ‘From Red to Green: Cuba Forced to Conserve Due to Economic Crisis’, Agriculture and Human Values 10(3): 31–4. Lambert, T. and Boerner, C. (1997) ‘Environmental Inequity: Economic Causes, Economic Solutions’, Yale Journal on Regulation 14(1): 195–234. Lavelle, M. and Coyle, M. (1992) ‘Unequal Protection: The Racial Divide in Environmental Law’, The National Law Journal S1–S2. Levins, R. (2005) ‘How Cuba is Going Ecological’, Capitalism Nature Socialism 16(3): 7–25. Lievesley, G. (2004) The Cuban Revolution: Past, Present and Future Perspectives. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. Ludlam, S. (2009) ‘Cuban Labour at 50: What About the Workers?’, Bulletin of Latin American Research 28(4): 542–57. Maal-Bared, R. (2006) ‘Comparing Environmental Issues in Cuba Before and After the Special Period: Balancing Sustainable Development and Sur- vival’, Environment International 32: 349–58. Maldonado, A. (2003) ‘Cuba’s Environment: Today and Tomorrow – An Action Plan’, Cuba in Transition Vol. 13. Papers and Proceedings of the Thirteenth Annual Meeting of the Association for the Study of the Cuban Economy (ASCE), Coral Gables, FL, 7–9 August. Martinez-Alier, J. (2003) The Environmentalism of the Poor: A Study of Ecological Conflicts and Valuation. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar. Mesa-Lago, C. (2002) ‘Growing Economic and Social Disparities in Cuba: Impact and Recommendations for Change’, Cuba Transition Project, University of Miami. at EASTERN MICHIGAN UNIV on February 28, 2013csp.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://csp.sagepub.com/ B E L L — E N V I R O N M E N T A L J U S T I C E I N C U B A 263 Mesa-Lago, C. (2005) ‘The Cuban Economy Today: Salvation or Damnation’, Cuba Transition Project, University of Miami. Mesa-Lago, C. (2006) ‘Assessing Cuba’s Economy: Current and Future Capac- ity to Provide Social Justice’, presentation to Canadian Foundation for the Americas Ottawa, June. Morris, E. (2008) ‘Poverty and Inequality in Cuba Today: The Policy Chal- lenge’, presentation at the International Institute for the Study of Cuba, London Metropolitan University, October. Nielsen, B. (2003) ‘Sex in the Cornfield: Tassel Emergence & Pollen Shed’, Corny News Network [http://www.kingcorn.org/news/timeless/Tassels. html]. Oliveras, R. and Ricardo Núñez, R. (2004) ‘Urban Segregation in Havana: Policies, Instruments and Results’, Paper presented at the seminar ‘Pov- erty and Social Policy in Cuba: Addressing the Challenges of Social and Economic Change’. ONE (2008) Statistical Yearbook of Cuba. Havana: Office of National Statistics. [www.ONE.cu] Pandey, K. D., Wheeler, D., Ostro, B., Deichmann, U., Hamilton, K. and Bolt, K. (2006) Ambient Particulate Matter Concentrations in Residential and Pollution Hotspot Areas of World Cities: New Estimates Based on the Global Model of Ambient Particulates (GMAPS). Washington DC: The World Bank. Pastor, J. M., Sadd, J. L. and Hipp, J. (2001) ‘Which Came First? Toxic Facil- ities, Minority Move-in, and Environmental Justice’, Journal of Urban Affairs 23(1): 1–21. Pellow, D. N. (2007) Resisting Global Toxics: Transnational Movements for Envi- ronmental Justice. Cambridge, MA and London: MIT Press. PinderHughes, R. (1996) ‘The Impact of Race on Environmental Quality: An Empirical and Theoretical Discussion’, Sociological Perspectives 39(2): 231–48. Porritt, J. ([2005] 2007) Capitalism: As if the World Matters. London: Earth- scan. Pulido, L. (1996) ‘A Critical Review of the Methodology of Environmental Racism Research’, Antipode 28: 142–5. Raby, D. L. (2006) Democracy and Revolution. London: Pluto Press. Ramirez, R. (2005) ‘State and Civil Society in the Barrios of Havana, Cuba: The Case of Pogolotti’, Environment and Urbanization 17(1): 147–70. Regueiro, L. and Alonso, A. (2001) ‘La Experiencia Cubana en la Lucha Con- tra la Pobreza’, in Las Tres Caras de la Pobreza: República Dominicana, Puerto Rico y Cuba. Investigación sobre la Situación Social, Económica y Política de la Sub-región de Habla Hispana del Caribe. Consejo Mundial de Iglesias. Rodríguez, J. L. (1983) ‘La Llamada Cubanología y el Desarrollo Económico de Cuba’, Temas de Economia Mundial No. 7: 131–53. at EASTERN MICHIGAN UNIV on February 28, 2013csp.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://csp.sagepub.com/ 264 C R I T I C A L S O C I A L P O L I C Y 3 1 ( 2 ) Rodríguez, J. L. and Carrizo Moreno, G. (1987) Erradicación de la Pobreza en Cuba. Havana: Editorial de Ciencias Sociales. Roman, P. (2003) Peoples Power: Cuba’s Experience with Representative Govern- ment. Oxford: Rowman & Littlefield. Rosset, P. and Benjamin, M. (1995) The Greening of the Revolution: Cuba’s Experiment with Organic Agriculture. Sydney: Ocean Press. Saney, I. (2004) Cuba: A Revolution in Motion. London: Zed Books. Sawyer, M. Q. (2006) Racial Politics in Post-Revolutionary Cuba. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Schlosberg, D. (2004) ‘Reconceiving Environmental Justice: Global Move- ments and Political Theories’, Environmental Politics 13(3): 517–40. Schlosberg, D. (2007) Defining Environmental Justice: Theories, Movements, and Nature. New York: Oxford University Press. Schnaiberg, A. and Gould, K. (2000) Environment and Society: The Enduring Conflict. New York: St. Martin’s Press. Stanley, A. (2009) ‘Just Space or Spatial Justice? Difference, Discourse, and Environmental Justice’, Local Environment 14(10): 999–1014. Sustainable Development Commission (2003) Mainstreaming Sustainable Regen- eration: A Call to Action. London: Sustainable Development Commission. Taylor, J. H. L. (2009) Inside El Barrio: A Bottom-up View of Neighborhood Life in Castro’s Cuba. Sterling, VA: Kumarian Press. UCC (1987) Toxic Waste and Race in the United States: A National Report on the Racial and Socioeconomic Characteristics of Communities with Hazardous Waste Sites. New York: United Church of Christ, Commission for Racial Justice. UNEP (United Nations Environment Programme) (1992) ‘Rio Declaration on Environment and Development’. Uriarte-Gaston, M. (2004) ‘Social Policy Responses to Cuba’s Economic Crisis of the 1990s’, Cuban Studies 35: 105–36. Walker, G. and Bulkeley, H. (2006) ‘Geographies of Environmental Justice’, Geoforum 37(5): 655–9. Walker, G. and Eames, M. (2006) ‘Environmental Inequalities: Cross-Cutting Themes for the ESRC/NERC Transdisciplinary Seminar Series 2006–8’, discussion paper. Whittle, D. and Rey Santos, O. (2006) ‘Protecting Cuba’s Environment: Efforts to Design and Implement Effective Environmental Laws and Poli- cies in Cuba’, Cuban Studies 37: 73–103. Wilkinson, R. and Pickett, K. (2009) The Spirit Level: Why More Equal Societies Almost Always Do Better. London: Allen Lane. World Bank (2009) ‘Environmental Data by Country’. World Wildlife Fund (2006) ‘Living Planet Report’. Gland, Switzerland: WWF International. Yaffe, H. (2009) Che Guevara: The Economics of Revolution. London: Palgrave Macmillan. at EASTERN MICHIGAN UNIV on February 28, 2013csp.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://csp.sagepub.com/ B E L L — E N V I R O N M E N T A L J U S T I C E I N C U B A 265  Karen Bell has worked as a community development worker for over 20 years on issues of disability equality, anti-racism, community empowerment, environmental justice and economic regeneration. Since 2005, she has been engaged in community-based research projects on these topics and currently works part-time at the School for Policy Studies, University of Bristol. Address: School for Policy Studies, University of Bristol, 8 Priory Road, Bristol BS8 1TZ, UK. email: karen.bell@bristol.ac.uk  at EASTERN MICHIGAN UNIV on February 28, 2013csp.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://csp.sagepub.com/ work_bwsxiltwznhrhjwfqzpm6v4du4 ---- Index action plan orders, 26 roY'usarial process. 13,70,93 alcohol problems, 25. 133, 134, 147 Alliance ofNon-govemmenw Organizations, 130 ancientwodd.l11 anti·social behaviour, 45 anti-social bebaviourorders, 164, 167 apologies,42, 86, 88, 135, 140, 143, 147 Argentina,S7 Australia: Aboriginal courts, 163 c~utioningcase.61 fIl.cilitators,70 &milygroup confc.rcncing, 113, 127, 137 incrcas.ing use of prison, 185 indigenous culturcs CIlStomaty law, 131 definition of crime.. 157-60 dispua: Iesolution, 115, 145 murder of wome~, 153 QlIetlt II Gj. 157-60 restorative justice, 29,81 introduction, 117 police and, 167,184 regulation, 184- victim traumas, 139 ),oungoffe:nders.147,148 b.u, 164,169,171,173 begging,45 Bdgiwn, 129 Bentham,Jeremy,35 Biden,] 0, 92 Bhgg,H,116,145,184 Blair, Tooy,34,36 bootca.mps, 170 Bottoms,A,112,119-20,166,174 BougainviUe.82 Braithwaite,]ohn, SO, 79, 111, 166, 110-1, 174,175 Buddhism, 111 bureaucr4C)',142 Canada: circles of support and accountability, 38-9, 163 sentencing circles. 113,117, 163 cautions, coodicionai cautions, 27-8 Chile, 87 Christie, NiLs, 9, 105 circle sentenciog,113, 117, 163 circles of support and accountability, 38--9, 90 civill2w systeIIUl, victims' role, 9 civil society, 19,36, 37,105,120,166,174, 175 dans, 112, 145 <:1"',54,112, 149, 164, 165,167,172, 175 co-existeocC!; JUcomplemc:nt:ary-approaeb~ coercion: coercion·oooseotstratcgies,l64 communities and, 177 neo-liberalismand, 169 offcnders,146-7 quali£icddefence, 57-60 state, 106 victims, 135 Coker,D,154,l64 colonialism, 153-4, 176 commonsense, 105--6,108-9, 122,131,161, 185 communication skills, 147--8 coatmUflitat:iaoism: civil liberties and, 35, 37-8, 40 eul.y tte2tises, 4 meming, 35-6 motalism, 121 New Labour, 34-5, 36, 37 reintegration, focus on, 121, 185 ri!;$tontive justice and, 34--40, 69 state and, 37-9 communities: absence of, 54-5 2ppropriate:panicipaots,I6-17,50-1 barriers, S5-6 chaos, 21-2 concept, 16 critique, 174-77 cultural attitudes, 157-60 dialogue, 40 emptiness, 22 engaging, ~7 190 Index communities (amI.): exclusionary communities, 61-2, 175 frngmaltedcommunitics, 91-5 G!tIJ!itlIdJtIji,19,119-22 heart of restorative! justice, 16-25 informaisanctions, 36-7 pi_SED, 17 pseudo-.--4, 109--17 over_intl -7 restitution m reparation restorative justice: communiarianism fttcomrnuniwiaoi.s.m complementary appfOJ.chcS IU comple~ mc:ntary approaches Core vt\lue5,40, 74,102 defitrltion, 1-2,102 development Judevclopmttlt of restOra· tivejusticc divctSion.122 divetsityof pmc:tices., 101-2 inclusiorwy emphasjs, 40 inte.mational business, 102-3,125-32 objectives, 6-7, 136, 169-70 pen>! policy framewoclt. 169-74 pre-(;oodirions, 89, 90-1 processes, 7-8 retributive/restOrative dichotomy I 40-4, 94,104-5 schobuship, 30-4,101 social movement, 183 theory v practice, 6, 26-40, 186 retribution: intemational justice, 8:>.-4 194 Index retribution (Cl)l1t.): just: desertS principle, 60--1, 62, 103,170, 183 paradigm. 3, 130 proportionality m proportionality of pun- ishmem rc:;toIlltivc justice and, 169-70 [etDbutive/tt:stOratlve dichotOmy. 40-4, 94,104-5 shift to, 124 Richards, K, 112-13, 122-3, 135 risk society, 32-3, 40, 107, 169, 171-4 Robben Island, 140 Rock,P,113 Rose,N,176 Rw.tnda: gd .. lJrpeourts. 15, 82, 84-6, 131, 178-80 public excl;UtiOns. 83 Sarah's law, 31 schoo~, 17,45,46-7,102-3 Scott Peck, Morgan.. 19-23 "ripC>, 133,138, 143, 148, 149,181,185 self-detc:nninatioD,117,118 sentencing $et QlIo prison cir.cle. sentencing, 163 COotcxtu:ill information, 43 clisproportionality,50 indetem:rinate sentences, 172 public opinion and, 62-3 pymmid :1ppt02ches. 48,79 re!>tonlcive justice:mel, 163 young offenders, 17 2-3 sentencing cizcles.ll.3. 117, 163 serious offences: crimes ag:alnsthumanity, 81-9, 178-80 domestic violenc::e, 75--81 homicide, 81 limits of restorative justice, 89-91 meaning. 72 restorative justice and, 49-50, 72-91, 172 ~tionaljustic~ 177-83 victim traumas, 138-41 sex offenders, 31, 38-9, 126,162,172 sc:xual violence, 81, 90--1, 138, 150, 152, 157-9 slwning. 31,115,120, 128, 133,145,149, 164,170-1 Shennan.La~enc~ lZ7 shuttlemediatiOD, 7.14. 59,61 sink estates, S6 socW capital, 53, 54 socilllconnectedness, 122, 131, 185 sochU engineering, S l-? social ineqwlity, 156-7 social justice. 11-12 social movements,11S,I86 social solidarity, 125, 177 South Afric:;a: apologi~, 140 TRC,82, 87-$, 102,178, 180-1 Spoin, 129 spo=r, 54 stakeholders,2, 8 sure! coercion, tOG commuaitarianism and, 37- 9 criminal justice and, 9 exdl.lsive deUnition of cmne, 103 Keynesianism,166 neo-liberalgovemance,l23-5 nightwatchman state, 166 pte-state: societies, 104, 110-11, 117 quasi-represenuti ... es, 185 rcguiation of restorative juscice, 106-7, 137--1!,165,184 .regulatory state, 166 u:prC!ltllLaUves, 7, 8, 137,138,185 role, 5, 162-7 state/civil society dichotomy, 105 stigmatisaaon, 32, 150, 152 sti~diuy magistr.l.lCS, 71 Stop and si!:U'Ch powcn, 167 Stubbs,J,156 T aoism, 111 TbJimcs Valley, 38-9, 70,127,136 ThatCher, Margaret,35 Timor Lesa=, 82, 182 TOnnics, Perdirwld, 19 transitionaljustic.e,15,82, 102, 177-83 truth,64, 83, 86, 109,112,117,179, 183--7 truth commissions, 15, 82, 178,180--2 Tsvangirai, Morgan, 89 Tutu, De:smond, 180 Umbte:it, Mark, 81 une:mployment, 11,165,172 United Nations, 30, 109, 115, 129-30 United StateS: crimi.o..a.ljustice, 126, 128 deolh p=>Ity, 81 dom~tic vio1ene<:, t 53 indigenonsculture:s, 113, 114-15. 154 Megan's law, 31 prison population, 31 racism, 92 rep:w.tion agreements, 61 restorative justice, 29, 81 sex offend~[S, 31 victims' rolc, 9,10 universalism,tO?, 109,131, 182, 185 Van Ness, Dan. 1-29 vandalism, 45 victim compensll.tloa orders, 14-15 victim impact statemcnts, 14-15, 43 victimsuppon services, 14-15 vktlms: 18th-cenwry England, 8 2S witne:lscs, 9. 143 civil law s~t'e[[1$, 9 closure, 59, 132 . coero.ao, 135 caaditioa.a1 cautions md, 27 crime victim surveys, 113,134 crimes ag.UI'lSl humanity and, 85-6 dialogue with offenders #r.dialogue empowenncu, 132. 135, 136, 142 healing II. healing ruslorical development of criInincl. justic~ 8--9 ideal victims, 132, 133-4 in"lU3lity,112 intemational criminal law Atld, 86 labelling. 133 offender-victim relationships hate crimes, 68.--9,155-6 inoommensunbility,157--60 inequalities, 15~7 socia1int:quality,15~7 violence~stwomen, 75-81,150-4 offende..rs as, 134,162-3 participation Jevels, 134-7 publiconi~toffcnecsand,140-1 radical feminism and, 77 reparation to 1« reparation rc;p.rqenLOl.tivc-'1, 18, 43. 141, 144, I SS ftstocative justice and usessmentofbene6c, 141-5 er:itiql.l~,132, 134--45 satisfaction., 132,144 ,haming.152, 159 stereotypeS. 133-4 stigma, 152 telling their stories, 142-3 traumas, 138-41 1l1dex 195 vengeful victims, 61-2, 66-7 victim-offender barricr:!l,10-11 victims' right move:me.nt, 112-13 viole:nce against women, 150-4 voluntarine:ss.57-9 Youth Offende:~P3..ncls Md,27 vittualcOtnmunities,16 vQIW)~riness, 57-60, 146--7 Wachtel, Ted,l-2 W::&ldman, E, 139, 140 Waluorf,L,179,181 WalkIate., S, 127 war c.rirn es, 82 "'hat woxks agenda.' 34, 127-8 Williams, N, t 45 Wright, M,136 x~ophobia, 175 Yolgt'lu people, 115, 145 young offenders: action plan orders, 26 apologies, 147 communication skills, 147--8 'rera.l youths,' 28, 56 indigenouscultw:eti,l86 minorv serious offenders, 172 Ne:wLabourpolicies, 127 New Zealand, 29,38 Northem Ixe1and, 29 parmts' rolein restorative justice., 56-7 . prison, 172-3 publicorderoffcnccs, 140-1 refe:nal orden, 27, 129, 146 rep:mtion orot:r::i, 26 resaciali.s2tion,52 lestorative justice and,S, 12~1 minority youths, 168 victims' reacdons, l44~5 victim participation, 136 whatwotks agenda, 127 ),Ou.U1 offcndq- p~m:h, 27, 129 yauch offe:nding teams, 26 youth res:o:a.tive disposals (YRDs), 2B YOllth SeMce Level Cue ~semcnt InventolY.171-2 Zeh<, How=!, 40. 41 zero-tolewu:e policing, 126, 128,1~9, 171 Zimbabwe:, 89-90 work_bxmpwqnlm5bwrdd22wd6hzeklu ---- Science Magazine SIGNALING Controlling blood flow in the liver High blood pressure in the liver created by fibrosis causes serious clinical illness. Blood pressure is regulated by nitric oxide, but this is depleted if hepatic sinusoidal endothelial cells are damaged. The scaffold protein b-arrestin 2 (b-Arr2) regulates the activity of endo- thelial cell nitric oxide synthase (eNOS) in rodent liver. Liu et al. found that in rodents, b-Arr2, which serves several functions in G protein–coupled receptor signaling, helps to control eNOS at endothelin receptors. b-Arr2 promoted the association of another protein called GIT1 with eNOS, which activates eNOS. Apparently, b-Arr2 and other signaling components form a signalsome near the endothe- lin receptors, which regulates eNOS function. Disruption of this signaling contributes to the liver injury and portal hypertension that cause lethal liver disease in humans. —LBR Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 117, 11483 (2020). MIGRATION Should I stay or should I go? The global upheaval of seasonal bird migration is an astonishing phenomenon. The European blackcap is a species of small songbird that shows great varia- tion in wanderlust. Delmore et al. collected DNA-sequencing data from blackcaps across their breeding range to deter- mine the genetic basis for variations in migratory behavior. The impulse to migrate and the distance and direction of travel are encoded in small genomic regions. Polymorphisms were found in genes for transcription factors such as Clock, Npas2, and Bma1, which are associated with circadian rhythm. A few genes linked to traits as varied 1 2 0 2 12 JUNE 2020 • VOL 368 ISSUE 6496 sciencemag.org S C I E N C E R E S E A R C H | I N S C I E N C E J O U R NA L S Edited by Caroline Ash and Jesse Smith I N O T H E R J O U R NA L S being dependent on the size of the nanocube and electrically tunable, the results demonstrate a powerful platform with which to develop sensors in what has been a challenging wavelength regime where molecular finger- prints reside. —ISO Science, this issue p. 1219 MOLECULAR MACHINES Ten rings on one axle Rotaxanes consist of molecu- lar rings threaded on a central axle. Most approaches to their synthesis have focused on introducing a single ring per axle. Qiu et al. now report a system- atic approach to threading up to 10 adjacent rings consecutively. The axle’s end groups were con- structed to attract free-floating rings when reduced and then to push those rings toward the cen- ter upon oxidation. Products of each successive reduction-oxi- dation cycle were characterized by nuclear magnetic resonance spectroscopy and mass spec- trometry. —JSY Science, this issue p. 1247 INSECT LOCOMOTION Robot on a wire Studying the free flight of insects using artificial systems such as tethered flight or flight in confined environments can cause the insect to fly in an unnatural way. Pannequin et al. report a cable robot consist- ing of an open cage mounted with cameras, which they call “lab-on-cables.” The cable robot moves automatically with the flying insect by using reactive controllers to track the insect’s flight in natural conditions with limited disturbance. Using this system, the researchers were able to study Agrotis ipsilon moths flying freely at speeds of up to 3 meters per second. —MML Sci. Robot. 5, eabb2890 (2020). ICE SHEETS Taking stock of our losses Earth’s ice sheets are melting and sea levels are rising, so it behooves us to understand bet- ter which climate processes are responsible for how much of the mass loss. Smith et al. estimated grounded and floating ice mass change for the Greenland and Antarctic ice sheets from 2003 to 2019 using satellite laser altimetry data from NASA’s ICESat and ICESat-2 satellites. They show how changing ice flow, melting, and precipitation affect different regions of ice and estimate that grounded-ice loss averaged close to 320 gigatons per year over that period and contributed 14 millimeters to sea level rise. —HJS Science, this issue p. 1239 P H O T O S ( F R O M L E F T ): D O M IN IQ U E M A R T IN E Z ; S W A P A N B A N IK / A L A M Y S T O C K P H O T O A cable-driven robot capable of autonomous tracking of free- flying insects in three dimensions GENETICS Big cat genomics T he lion may be the king of beasts, but over the past ~14,000 years, their range has decreased substan- tially and many current populations are in decline. To understand the historical population genomics of lions, de Manuel et al. sequenced cave lion remains from ~30,000 years ago, several historic specimens from extinct populations over the past ~500 years, and samples from extant populations. From this, they were able to reconstruct relationships among lion populations over time. No evidence of gene flow between cave lions and recent lion populations was detected. Modern lion groups that diverged into northern and southern lineages show evidence of admixture, especially in extant central African populations. These data could be valuable not only because they indicate the relationships between modern and extinct populations but also because they reveal a historical level of inbreeding that could be rel- evant to conservation efforts. —LMZ Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 117, 10927 (2020). Published by AAAS o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 h ttp ://scie n ce .scie n ce m a g .o rg / D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://science.sciencemag.org/ responsiveness to civilian concerns. Wood et al. examined whether the introduction of a procedural justice training program for police officers in Chicago had an impact on encounters between police and civilians. It was found that fewer complaints were registered against officers who received the training, and trained officers were less likely to use force dur- ing civilian encounters. These findings have implications for designing scalable interventions that build police legitimacy. —TSR Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 117, 9815 (2020). MACHINE LEARNING Learning macro from micro Determining atomic structural correlations in condensed- phase systems is crucial for understanding material properties and their behavior single-stranded DNA that trans- ferred onto a gold nanoparticle bound inside the frame. On release, the particles could then undergo complementary strand binding with smaller gold nanoparticles to form clusters. By using different inks within the frame, gold particles of dif- ferent sizes could be assembled onto the central particle. The angles between the particles in these heterogeneous clusters could also be controlled through steric effects. —PDS ACS Nano. 10.1021/acsnano.0c00607 (2020). PSYCHOLOGY Procedural justice improves policing Research on procedural justice emphasizes the importance of treating people fairly regardless of the outcome they receive. Procedural justice strategies include increased transpar- ency, communication, and as hyperphagia and fat deposi- tion, learning and memory, and wing length also appear to be under strong selection to rapidly evolve new behaviors. The suite of blackcap migra- tory genes is distinctive, and it appears that there are many ways to genetically program migration in birds. —CA eLife 9, e54462 (2020). NANOMATERIALS Pattering nanoparticles with DNA origami Complementary DNA strands can be used to assemble nanoparticles through spe- cific connections, but creating multivalent directional connec- tions is still challenging. Xiong et al. used DNA origami—a two-dimensional open square and a three-dimensional tetra- hedron framework—to position DNA linkers on nanoparticles. These molecular stamping, or MOST, frames were “inked” with 12 JUNE 2020 • VOL 368 ISSUE 6496 1 2 0 3S C I E N C E sciencemag.org at the macroscale. It represents one of the central challenges in modern statistical mechan- ics because of the complex collective behavior emerging from microscopic many-body interactions. Using two classical condensed-phase models, a Lennard-Jones system and a hard-sphere fluid, Craven et al. show that machine learn- ing methods trained on a set of optimally short molecular dynamics simulations can predict radial distribution func- tions with increased accuracy by an order of magnitude or even greater compared with tra- ditional analytical approaches. The proposed methodology is general and could be applied more broadly across diverse condensed-phase systems. —YS J. Phys. Chem. Lett. 10.1021/ acs.jpclett.0c00627 (2020). NEUROSCIENCE Inositol-triphosphate receptors in axons Inositol-triphosphate (IP 3 ) receptors regulate the intracel- lular calcium concentration in the somatodendritic com- partment of central neurons. Whether axons also possess functional IP 3 receptors and what impact their activation might have are not known. Cerebellar Purkinje cells offer an ideal model because they contain a high level of IP 3 recep- tors. Using chromophore tags that release IP 3 when irradiated, Gomez et al. found that func- tional IP 3 receptors are present in the entire axon. Different axon regions displayed different IP 3 -producing pathways, and IP 3 receptor activation had differ- ent consequences depending on receptor localization. For instance, IP 3 receptor activation in synaptic terminals caused neurotransmitter release, and receptor activation in the axon initial segment blocked action potential firing. IP 3 receptor– linked signaling pathways may therefore be important in con- trolling axon functions. —PRS Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U.S.A. 117, 11097 (2020). Gir lions are a remnant population of a few hundred northern lions, mostly found in Africa, that are just surviving in India. Published by AAAS o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 h ttp ://scie n ce .scie n ce m a g .o rg / D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://science.sciencemag.org/ Procedural justice improves policing Tage S. Rai DOI: 10.1126/science.368.6496.1202-e (6496), 1202-1203.368Science ARTICLE TOOLS http://science.sciencemag.org/content/368/6496/1202.5 CONTENT RELATED file:/content/sci/368/6496/twil.full PERMISSIONS http://www.sciencemag.org/help/reprints-and-permissions Terms of ServiceUse of this article is subject to the is a registered trademark of AAAS.ScienceScience, 1200 New York Avenue NW, Washington, DC 20005. The title (print ISSN 0036-8075; online ISSN 1095-9203) is published by the American Association for the Advancement ofScience Science. No claim to original U.S. Government Works Copyright © 2020 The Authors, some rights reserved; exclusive licensee American Association for the Advancement of o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 h ttp ://scie n ce .scie n ce m a g .o rg / D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://science.sciencemag.org/content/368/6496/1202.5 http://www.sciencemag.org/help/reprints-and-permissions http://www.sciencemag.org/about/terms-service http://science.sciencemag.org/ work_bztzg73btrfp7hosyxz62dj4rm ---- wp-p1m-39.ebi.ac.uk Params is empty 404 sys_1000 exception wp-p1m-39.ebi.ac.uk no 221738956 Params is empty 221738956 exception Params is empty 2021/04/06-03:20:37 if (typeof jQuery === "undefined") document.write('[script type="text/javascript" src="/corehtml/pmc/jig/1.14.8/js/jig.min.js"][/script]'.replace(/\[/g,String.fromCharCode(60)).replace(/\]/g,String.fromCharCode(62))); // // // window.name="mainwindow"; .pmc-wm {background:transparent repeat-y top left;background-image:url(/corehtml/pmc/pmcgifs/wm-nobrand.png);background-size: auto, contain} .print-view{display:block} Page not available Reason: The web page address (URL) that you used may be incorrect. Message ID: 221738956 (wp-p1m-39.ebi.ac.uk) Time: 2021/04/06 03:20:37 If you need further help, please send an email to PMC. Include the information from the box above in your message. Otherwise, click on one of the following links to continue using PMC: Search the complete PMC archive. Browse the contents of a specific journal in PMC. Find a specific article by its citation (journal, date, volume, first page, author or article title). http://europepmc.org/abstract/MED/ work_c422yiyhavdmvbun7qzztb4nwi ---- Newcastle University ePrints Walton A. Justice, Authority, and the World Order. Journal of Global Ethics 2009, 5(3), 215-230. Copyright: This is an Author's Accepted Manuscript of an article published in Journal of Global Ethics, December 2009, copyright Taylor & Francis, available online at: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/17449620903403317 Always use the definitive version when citing. Further information on publisher website: http://www.tandfonline.com Date deposited: 11th October 2013 Version of file: Author final This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 3.0 Unported License ePrints – Newcastle University ePrints http://eprint.ncl.ac.uk javascript:ViewPublication(194585); http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/17449620903403317 http://www.tandfonline.com/ http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/3.0/deed.en_GB http://eprint.ncl.ac.uk/ A. Walton 1 RESEARCH ARTICLE Justice, Authority, and the World Order A. Walton 1 Department of Politics and International Studies, University of Warwick, Coventry, UK Abstract: This paper defends the pertinence of global justice in the contemporary world. It accepts, for the sake of argument, Nagel’s view that matters of justice arise only when political authority is asserted or exercised and, connectedly, his rejection of the cosmopolitan thesis. However, it challenges his conclusion that considerations of justice do not apply beyond the state. It argues that on any plausible account of the relationship between authority and justice international institutions, such as the World Trade Organisation, are now authoritative in the right way to justify their evaluation from the point of view of justice. Keywords: Justice, Authority, International Institutions, World Trade Organisation. Introduction Despite it often being said that we live in a global world, where borders are of decreasing significance, authors writing on matters of justice often still ‘assume that the basic structure is that of a closed society...self-contained and as having no relations with other societies’ (Rawls 2005, 12). This may be somewhat unfair. ‘Global justice’ is receiving an increasing attention in literature. Yet, it is also true that many are sceptical of this idea. In this paper I will challenge the views of a leading global justice sceptic, Thomas Nagel. The argument will be constructed as follows. First, I will introduce the global justice debate. Second, I will outline Nagel’s objection to the idea of global justice, which focuses on asserting an important place for authority in matters of justice. Third, without challenging Nagel’s overarching normative thesis I will argue that we should not accept his conclusion that there is no justice beyond the state because even if we accept the pivotal place he attributes to authority in matters of justice on any plausible understanding of the relationship there is now reason to think this has global application. In section four I address another dimension of the relationship between justice and authority: the idea that the realisation of the former requires an enforcement mechanism to provide assurance. I argue that even if this claim is valid it, for two reasons, does not follow that issues of justice do not have global application in the contemporary world. 1. Justice Throughout modern history the sovereign nation-state has been considered the primary, and often sole, site of justice and such thinking remained prevalent even amongst notable political theorists at the turn of the century (cf. Rawls 1999a; Rawls 1999b). This view takes a particular stance on two matters. First, there is the distinction between institutional and pre-institutional views of justice. The former holds that issues of justice arise only within certain types of associational schemes. The latter holds that justice is 1 Andrew Walton works at the Department of Politics and International Studies at the University of Warwick. Email: Andrew.J.Walton@warwick.ac.uk Journal of Global Ethics 2 a pre-institutional ideal which applies to all people in all places regardless of their institutional affiliations. Those that affirm the idea that justice applies only within states take an institutional approach. Second, there is the question of whether the institutional view of justice has application beyond the domestic level; whether, that is, global institutions qualify as ‘institutions’ such that they should be regulated by considerations of justice. Are they, in other words, the appropriate kind of institutions for issues of justice to arise? The state-based view answers “no” to this question. Given this typology, it is possible to challenge the state-based view in two ways. First, it could be argued that the institutional approach to justice favours its application at the global level because global affairs are relevantly institutional (cf. Pogge 1989; Beitz 1999). I shall return to this issue. It could also be challenged for holding that justice is an institutional virtue. Associational ties, it could be argued, are simply arbitrary features by which to structure justice. This is the view of many cosmopolitans (cf. Steiner 1994; Singer 2002; Caney 2005). Their challenge, in short, is that contingent facts (such as the geographical dominions of states) should not influence the life prospects of an individual because they are undeserved and therefore arbitrary from the moral point of view. The cosmopolitan thesis is certainly a forceful one. There have been a number of attempts to respond to it. Rawls gave his own reasons for refuting it (Rawls 1999b, 117-118). These, however, have been the subject of much criticism (cf. Martin 2006; Pogge 2006). The cosmopolitan claim has also been challenged by so-called ‘reciprocity’ accounts, which claim that justice applies only to schemes of cooperation of a certain sort and is therefore limited to the domestic realm where social interaction is of the right kind (cf. Sangiovanni 2007, 19-38). However, this will not suffice to defend the state-based view of justice for one of two reasons: either the definition of cooperation is relatively weak, in which case it is hard to deny that the relevant kinds of cooperation exist across borders, or the definition is relatively stringent (the approach adopted by Sangiovanni), in which case it becomes more difficult to believe that this is the only condition that initiates concerns of justice. Cooperation-based accounts of justice (especially of the reciprocity form) also face a more significant criticism (one that cosmopolitans are likely to endorses); namely, explaining why any concern is owed to those unable to contribute (such as the severely disabled). In addition, there have been other attempts to justify the traditional focus on the state as, at least, the historical focal point for considerations of justice, such as Julius’ assertion that different types of interpersonal co- option raise a requirement of justice (Julius 2006, 187-192). However, this too suffers from a major problem; namely, explaining why some types of co-option meet the criteria but others do not and, perhaps more importantly, why only co-option and not pure coercion require justification. 2. Justice and Authority This challenge to the idea of global justice is set forth by Thomas Nagel (2005). There are two parts to his position: a response to the cosmopolitan thesis and a claim that principles of justice do not apply to international institutions. He affirms, that is, the institutional approach to justice and the answer “no” to the question of whether this has application at the global level. In this section I will outline Nagel’s view. The challenge cosmopolitans establish for those that restrict the scope of justice to the state is this: if a domestic/international split in moral principles is to be affirmed its defender must show, as Caney puts it, ‘a reason can be given as to why the two contexts are morally disanalogous’ (Caney 2005, 66). Nagel attempts to meet this challenge by citing what he believes to be a distinctive feature: authority, by which he means, broadly, an entity that rules A. Walton 3 over a population (Nagel 2005, 120-121). Nagel suggests two reasons for thinking the existence of an authority is important. First, Nagel highlights what we may call Hobbes’ dilemma (Nagel 2005, 115-117). Hobbes argued that justice – a set of rules that served everyone’s self-interest if conformed to – was possible only with the assurance of widespread conformity. Such coordinated conduct of a large population can be achieved, Hobbes thought, only with a sovereign power. The point also extends to non-egoist theories of justice. All such conceptions rely on maintaining patterns of conduct and this, Nagel maintains, ‘requires the external incentive provided by the sovereign’ because it only needs a small number of defectors to unravel an entire system (Nagel 2005, 115-116). While domestic states do have such an actor, the lack of a global sovereign, the argument continues, renders global justice an illusion. I shall address the strength of this claim in section four. In this and the next section I shall focus on the second reason Nagel offers for supposing there is something unique about relations under authority (Nagel 2005, 126-130). He does not think, departing from Hobbes here, that the international sphere is a non-moral zone because he concedes that individuals have some human rights that do not depend on institutional relations. However, Nagel has a restricted view of the duties owed to others to whom we are not related through ties of authority: these consist of humanitarian duties and negative claims (such as the right to bodily integrity). By contrast, socio-economic rights and duties – the positive obligations of justice – are ‘fully associative’ (Nagel 2005, 127). They are ‘something we owe through our shared institutions only to those with whom we stand in a strong political relationship’ (Nagel 2005, 121). Why? It is due, Nagel thinks, to the particular involvement of citizen will in relation to authority. Authorities invoke our will by exercising power in our name and commanding our active cooperation in upholding the laws they prescribe. Of significance is the ‘complex fact – that we are both putative joint authors of the coercively imposed system, and subject to its norms’ (Nagel 2005, 128). That our will is invoked in this manner gives us a certain standing to ask for justification of the enforced rules. Moreover, it places us in a unique relationship with those with whom we share the position. As we are all equally subject to the parameters and requirements of the framework imposed in our collective name we are entitled to demand treatment as an equal. We are entitled to ask why the imposed framework places us in a particular social position and whether this displays consideration equivalent to that shown to our fellow citizens; otherwise our will has been co-opted to serve others. It is not, then, as cosmopolitan theorists assert, inequality per se that is objected to; it is imposed frameworks that generate inequalities which reflect unequal treatment. It is, in other words, the system of rights, rules, and distribution that invoke our collective will which requires legitimating in egalitarian form. The positive demands of justice this creates are an issue arising solely in the context of such authority because this puts ‘citizens...into a relation that they do not have with the rest of humanity, an institutional relation which must then be evaluated by the special standards of fairness and equality that fill out the content of justice’ (Nagel 2005, 120). In short, the cosmopolitan question is this: What makes the domestic realm morally distinct from the international? The second part of Nagel’s response has three components: a normative premise (N); a factual premise (F); and an ensuing conclusion (C). The argument is this: N: It is only an authority relation that raises the particular positive demands of socio- economic justice. F: Domestic institutions meet the criteria for issues of justice to arise – i.e. they are authorities in the relevant sense – but international ones do not. C: There is no justice beyond the state. Journal of Global Ethics 4 With other aims in this paper I do not have space to arbitrate between institutional and pre-institutional views of justice. For what it is worth, I believe some version of Nagel’s normative thesis is correct. In the dispute between the two positions on whether justice extends beyond the state though, it is sufficient to accept his normative position for the sake of argument because even on its own terms it fails to substantiate the negative conclusion. As I will now show, Nagel’s argument gains its purchase by remaining ambiguous in what he means by N. When his claim is disambiguated Nagel faces a dilemma: either he can maintain that justice does not apply at the global level by making implausible claims about the relationship between justice and authority or he can affirm a plausible account of this relationship but must then accept that it has application to international institutions. On any plausible understanding of N, that is, F is unsustainable and C, therefore, is not valid. 3. Justice, Authority, and the World Order 3.1. In essence, Nagel claims that because authority invokes the will of a governed population it is the initiator of concerns of justice. This, however, is an ambiguous claim and cannot be assessed without some further definition of what qualifies an actor as an authority in the relevant sense, or, perhaps more specifically, without more detail with respect to what constitutes invoking citizen will in the required way. There are, I think, three conceptions of authority Nagel might be advocating as the necessary condition for issues of justice to arise. First, it might be bodies with authorised power. Perhaps, that is, Nagel thinks that we must be, in a sense, co-authors of the rules that regulate society (at least indirectly by electing the government that devises them) for a collective framework to implicate citizen will in the appropriate sense. Second, Nagel could be referring to actors that assert the right to rule, bodies, that is, that claim they are justified in regulating citizens’ lives and that citizens, consequently, have a duty to obey them. The will is implicated insofar as citizens have reason to comply with its dictates. Third, it may be that authority is meant to imply any actor enforcing conformity with the law and rules. The rules established for the collective are of the collective insofar as they embody the non-voluntary framework in which citizens live their lives and which they must obey. By having no choice but to uphold and conform to them their will is procured. In this section I will argue that neither of the first two offers a plausible understanding of the connection between justice and authority but that while the third is more palatable employing it to defend N will not allow Nagel to maintain his conclusions on global justice because F is not sustainable on this definition. 3.2. Before I expand upon this argument it is worth pausing briefly to highlight the distinctive nature of the challenge I pose Nagel here. I am not the first author to criticise his views but, as a review of other critiques of his work will now show, the particular formulation of my critique is uniquely able to disarm his position because my view is sensitive to different possible interpretations of Nagel, while other criticisms are wedded to particular readings of his argument. There are several problems with the recent literature on Nagel, because his views are not always interpreted altogether charitably. A number of authors have characterised Nagel as suggesting that justice is initiated by coercion (cf. Caney 2008, 490; Pevnick 2008, 400). However, as will become clear in what follows (especially section 3.6.) and as noted by some others (cf. Sangiovanni 2007, 14-19), it is not obvious that Nagel equates authority with coercion, and a critique of his position is more forceful to the extent that it does not depend on such a disputed interpretation. A. Walton 5 Similarly, other critics who recognise the aforementioned ambiguity in Nagel’s position do not consider the alternative readings in a fair light. For example, although Julius (2006) and Sangiovanni (2007) note that Nagel could be interpreted as implying that justice arises in the context of an authority that makes some claim about the right to rule neither of them specify the authority relation in the sense that Nagel means it. Julius thinks it involves an equilibrium point between state claims of legitimacy and citizen acceptance of the law as having moral force (Julius 2006, 181). However, this conception of authority does not give a fundamental role to citizen acceptance. The only issue of relevance is how the authority sees itself. As such, Julius, who often focuses on the attitude of citizens (Julius 2006, 182, 186), misreads Nagel’s view. Sangiovanni’s interpretation is more promising but he argues that the claim right to rule is best interpreted as those institutions which establish non-voluntary rules (Sangiovanni 2007, 16-17). However, he dismisses too swiftly the idea that Nagel might be making the distinct claim that justice pertains to authorities that take a certain attitude to their citizens. Perhaps more importantly, other critics have neglected to highlight the ambiguity in Nagel’s claim about what constitutes an authority in the relevant sense. Paying attention to this ambiguity is crucial for disarming his position because any critique focused on a particular reading of Nagel (any, in fact, that considers a non-exhaustive list of the possible interpretations of Nagel’s account of authority) leaves Nagel easily able to escape by claiming he meant to imply an alternative conception of the justice-authority relation. 2 Those who interpret Nagel as offering a coercion-based account (cf. Caney 2008, 490; Pevnick 2008, 400) suffer this problem because Nagel can claim he meant to imply that justice is initiated by authorities that claim a right to rule or that are authorised by citizen consent. Those who claim that Nagel’s view can be cast as either a coercion-based account or one focused on authorities that claim a right to rule (cf. Julius 2006, 181; Abizadeh 351-352) suffer this problem because Nagel can claim he meant to imply authorities that are authorised by citizen consent. Given this difficulty, the most promising strategy for critique, therefore, is to distinguish the different possible interpretations of Nagel’s account of authority and show that each is either implausible as a conception of the conditions for justice to apply or fails to deliver the conclusion Nagel affirms because global institutions are authoritative in the appropriate sense. There are also a number of other ways my comments on Nagel depart from ideas offered in previous literature but these can be addressed in due course. With the major discrepancies in other accounts and the distinct nature of the challenge I pose Nagel highlighted I can now turn to formulating this argument in full. 3.3. Before addressing the conceptions of authority directly consider the following example: Pure Tyranny: The citizens of Country M live under the rule of a tyrant. The laws and policies that exist are those that he commanded. They are designed to keep the tyrant in power (censorship, no elections, the banning of political opposition, state- authorised torture and arbitrary arrest) and serve his interests at the expense of the people (serfdom, education for obedience to hierarchy, and lavish expenditures on monuments in his honour while the people starve). These are enforced by armed forces. 2 It should be noted here that not all the existing critiques of Nagel aim to provide a conclusive refutation of his view. Some, such as Sangiovanni (2007), criticise it primarily as a prelude to offering an alternative account of the conditions that initiate justice (and therefore restrict its application to the domestic sphere). This, of course, is merely a matter of having a different aim to that of this article but it does mean that conclusive refutation of Nagel has remained elusive. Journal of Global Ethics 6 Country M is unjust. Few, I think, will dispute that. There is certainly some form of authority so Nagel’s broad premise is upheld. Moreover, as we can acknowledge the existence of injustice it is clear the issue of justice is pertinent. Let us explore now which of the above conceptions can sustain this conclusion. 3.4. Some have thought that authority essentially amounts to authorised power. 3 Political institutions are unique, in part, because they employ coercion to enforce their laws but as coercion is typically deemed troublesome it is thought some special justification is required. One position on this is that the coercion of governments is unlike other forms because it is legitimised through citizen agreement. By collectively accepting an authority or a set of rules we give normative weight to the power to enforce. Our will is invoked in a very obvious way here and it may be this necessity for our authorisation that raises an egalitarian concern, possibly on the grounds that being entrusted with such power places a duty upon the authority to act responsibly, something that would entail fair treatment of each subject. Although this is the least emphasised connection between authority and justice Nagel seems to acknowledge there are suggestions it is what he deems of import. ‘Justice’, he states, ‘requires a collectively imposed social framework’ (Nagel 2005, 140) and when arguing present global institutions are not an appropriate site for justice his reasoning includes the thought that ‘they do not ask for the kind of authorization by individuals that carries with it a responsibility to treat all those individuals in some sense equally’ (Nagel 2005, 138). On this view Nagel’s argument would read as follows: N1: It is only citizen-authorised coercion that raises the particular positive demands of socio-economic justice. F1: Domestic institutions meet the criteria for issues of justice to arise – i.e. they are citizen-authorised coercive bodies – but international ones do not. C1: There is no justice beyond the state. This argument, however, is clearly false because neither premise is persuasive. F1 is not persuasive because even if it is correct in asserting that global institutions do not meet the criterion it is not correct in claiming that domestic governments do any better, at least not all of them. In order to be consistent, then, the conclusion would need to read that justice applies in some states but not others. This, however, does not defend a generic state-based view of justice and it does not align with our intuitions on where justice is at issue even in the domestic context. Nor does it align with our normative intuitions. The view would suggest that Country M is not a site in which we should be concerned with justice because citizens here have not authorised the tyrant’s power (they have not even had the opportunity to do so). This idea of invoking the will, in short, does not align with our intuitions concerning when issues of justice arise. 4 3 It is perhaps worth noting that this is a rather obscure view of authority. For a good review of its difficulties see J. Raz. 1990. Introduction. In Authority, ed. J. Raz, 1-19. (Oxford: Basil Blackwell). It is, nonetheless, one view of authority that has a clear connection to invoking citizen will so it is worth discussion here. 4 It is worth noting that the role of authorisation might have other functions in questions of justice. It might, for instance, be used to test whether a regime is just, for example by asking whether it is a regime to which individuals (á la Locke and Kant) (or possibly hypothetical individuals (á la Rawls)) could consent. We can, that is, state that the reason why the Tyrant’s regime is unjust is because citizens or hypothetical individuals could not consent to it. Such questions, however, do not pertain to the issue of what conditions initiate justice. Neither of these ideas, for reasons similar to those made about actual citizen authorisation, can offer plausible explanations of what initiates justice. A. Walton 7 3.5. The second conception is essentially that expressed by Raz and is the common idea of ‘authority over persons as centrally involving a right to rule, where that is understood as correlated with an obligation to obey on the part of those subject to the authority’ (Raz 1986, 23). The thought here is that an authority is an actor that claims its ‘utterances are themselves reasons for action’ (Raz 1986, 35) and that we should, we in fact have a duty to, adhere to them not because we will otherwise be forced to or because an authority adds extra weight to existing reasons for action but because they emanate from the particular source (Raz 1990). As such deferent alignment of our will is invoked it is necessary, for the demand to have any weight, that the authority can substantiate its claim to legitimacy and this can only be achieved by showing us equal treatment. 5 This is much closer to the idea Nagel seems to endorse. ‘Justice applies’, he says, ‘only to a form of organization that claims political legitimacy’, only to frameworks designed for citizens by an actor ‘aspiring to command their acceptance of its authority even when they disagree with the substance of its decisions’ (Nagel 2005, 140). The system’s ‘requirements claim our active cooperation’, and this differs from the manner in which our laws relate to outsiders because the latter are not ‘asked to accept and uphold those laws’ (Nagel 2005, 129- 130). On this view Nagel’s argument would read as follows: N2: It is only the existence of an actor claiming it has a right to govern the actions of citizens and, therefore, that citizens have a duty to comply with its dictates that raises the particular positive demands of socio-economic justice. F2: Domestic institutions meet the criteria for issues of justice to arise – i.e. they are actors that claim a right to rule and a duty of citizen compliance – but international ones do not. C2: There is no justice beyond the state. There are two problems with this argument. First, it is not clear that F2 is sustainable. Provided we separate the assertion of the right to govern from the ability to enforce, it might plausibly be suggested that the directives of the World Health Organisation or the International Labour Organisation involve a claim that the institution has the expertise to guide conduct and even that we have some form of duty to obey (particularly in the case of the latter). It certainly cannot be denied that the UN, especially in the instance of human rights, claims such authority. Perhaps more problematic is the evident falsity of N2, which can be seen by returning to the example set forth in 3.3. Here we are confident that concerns of justice are at issue. However, the ‘authority’ does not assert any right to rule or that the people have any putative duty to obey. He makes no claim that he is a legitimate guide for their actions and he makes no suggestion that because his guidance is legitimate citizens have an exclusionary reason to follow his dictates. Nagel considers a problem of this kind when he addresses the question of colonial rule (Nagel 2005, 129n14). He suggests that issues of justice do arise in such instances once we take ‘a broad interpretation of what it is for a society to be governed in the name of its members’ (Nagel 2005, 129n14). ‘If a colonial or occupying power claims political authority over a population, it purports not to rule by force alone’, Nagel continues, ‘it is providing and enforcing a system of law that those subject to it are expected to uphold as participants, and 5 It is worth noting that Raz does not endorse the conclusion that egalitarianism issues from the existence of authorities of this kind (on which see Raz 1986, 217–44). However, others do affirm the connection (see, for instance, Dworkin 2001, 1) and it is evident (based on quotes noted earlier in this paper) that if Nagel does mean to endorse this conception of authority then he does believe the demand for equal concern issues from it. Journal of Global Ethics 8 which is intended to serve their interests’ (Nagel 2005, 129n14). It is a little unclear to me what Nagel means here. 6 It could, I think, be one of two things. It could be the claim that colonial powers did make some assertion that they were the legitimate authority of colonised peoples. Simply stated this claim is empirically inaccurate at least in some instances. Alternatively, it could be that colonial powers can be thought to have purported to rule not by force alone if we relax the stringency of the idea. Perhaps, that is, colonial powers could be considered to have implicitly suggested that they were acting in the name of colonised peoples and this is sufficient. I still doubt this empirical claim because there are instances of colonial rule that do not meet it. Whatever the actual history though, the suggestion that justice relies in some way on this claim must still be false because we can imagine scenarios where no such claim is even implicitly made, such as Country M, but where we are sure justice is at issue. In essence, Nagel faces the following problem. He could formulate the suggestion as asserting that we relax the stringency so far that it includes all authorities that command conformity, in which case it amounts to no more than suggesting that questions of justice arise in the context of all non-voluntary institutions (the subject of the following subsection). Alternatively, he could make a distinct claim about some more stringent criteria associated with claiming a right to rule but however this is defined as different from the first possibility it will always leave space for some tyranny scenarios that do not meet it, in which case it will exclude instances where we are sure justice is at issue. Either, then, Nagel can assert N2 and maintain that issues of justice arise neither in the global order nor in (at least some instances of) tyranny or we can seek a view that accommodates the last of these and test its validity in the present international system. I will proceed on the assumption that most people will feel inclined towards the second of these options. 3.6. The final conception of the relationship between authority and justice I will discuss here is the contention that the latter is initiated by the unique demands made on citizen will by non-voluntary institutions. This is essentially the thought that what makes a political institution unique is that, to all intents and purposes, we have no choice but to obey it or even in whether we continue to live under its rule. Perhaps it is this special circumstance that Nagel thinks gives rise to issues of justice: because we are obliged to accept the rules of an authority and the social position they place us in, we are owed (equal) consideration in their design. Before assessing this view it is necessary to clarify a number of its components. First, the term non-voluntary here does not imply a situation in which individuals have literally no option to act otherwise but, rather, refers to a state of affairs in which one conforms because non-conformity is unreasonably costly. It follows Olsaretti’s suggestion that ‘a choice is voluntary if and only if it is not made because there is no acceptable alternative’ (Olsaretti 2004, 139). In the domestic context this is manifest in the fact that there are penalties for breaking the law and emigration is no more than a Hobson’s choice for most. This is not, as some might suggest, an attempt to employ a controversial thesis on what it means for state institutions to be non-voluntary. 7 It is the rationale Rawls relies upon (Rawls 2005, 136, 136n4) and it was the substance of Hume’s criticisms of Locke’ tacit consent thesis, in which the former points out that obedience to rules aboard a ship on which one did not choose to sail is not voluntary just because one is free to jump into the sea (Hume 1777, 485). Moreover, the alternative – that state institutions are non-voluntary in the sense that there is literally no alternative to conformity – is highly implausible because the possibilities of breaking the law and emigrating do exist (there is even a right to the latter). If justice only 6 I thank David Stevens for pushing me to think about Nagel’s assertion here in more depth. 7 I thank Ed Page for pushing me to respond to this challenge and highlighting that the idea of non-voluntariness here required more detail. A. Walton 9 arose in the literal absence of such possibilities it would only be at issue in extreme totalitarian states, if at all (given even the strictest regimes cannot actually stop people breaking the law). The view, then, is coherent only on the formulation that a non-voluntary system raises unique concerns because we have no reasonable alternative to conformity. 8 Second, it must be noted that this is not the claim made by some (cf. Blake 2001) that justice arises in the context of coercion. The view is similar and they are interesting for similar reasons: both involve certain types of impositions on people. However, they are distinct in what types of rules and regulation can be deemed concerns of justice. Coercion focuses on rules backed by the sanction of force. Non-voluntariness focuses on all rules that command conformity by establishing unreasonable alternatives to obedience. This includes but is not exhausted by coercion. The following points, therefore, apply to coercion-based accounts but are more extensive. There are a number of reasons for my focus on non- voluntariness. First, as I will show, Nagel’s choice of wording seems to suggest it is non- voluntariness he deems of relevance. Second, it is a more plausible idea about where justice is at issue. This is partly backed by the support for a broader interpretation from key authors, such as Rawls, who focused on ‘a public system of rules’ that was meant to include the non- coercive institution of the family (Rawls 1999a, 47 and 10 respectively) and Williams, who argues that Rawls’ intended focus was on all rules that could be made the property of public knowledge (Williams 1998, 233). It is also backed, following Williams’ observations, by the fact that only by interpreting the point in this manner can we properly address issues such as gender justice which is violated most through informal social sanctions (which are not coercive but are non-voluntary in the sense used here). Third, it is important to note the particular reason for thinking non-voluntariness raises a demand for equal treatment. As I note above, it is of concern because it involves a certain type of imposition on people. In particular, non-voluntary rules establish the framework and the distribution of rights and burdens under which individuals must live their lives. Because they are placed in a particular social position by these rules they are entitled to ask for justification and they are entitled to demand that they are treated equally. Otherwise a system has been imposed upon them that invokes their will for the benefit of others and this violates Kant’s famous maxim that people should not be treated as a means. This background justification for the normative significance of non-voluntary institutions is important because it is often overlooked, especially by those who focus only on the coercion-based understanding of the idea. Some attribute the significance of coercion to the manner in which it restricts an individual’s options. They then object to the claim that state coercion requires justification because this, unlike normal forms of coercion is actually a facilitator of options, justified by its positive consequences (cf. Pevnick 2008, 401-402). However, this misconstrues the significance of coercion. 9 It is not merely the fact that one’s option set is 8 It is sometimes objected to this cost-based understanding of voluntariness that an such conception faces a problematic dilemma: either accession to highly attractive offers (such as being paid a billion pounds to tie someone else’s shoelaces together) can be deemed non-voluntary because the alternatives are unreasonably costly (which seems to undermine the force of the term’s meaning) or the theory needs to set an objective baseline for what counts as an unacceptable alternative (a notoriously controversial task). For what it is worth I think a plausible account of the latter can be given. For the purposes here, however, I believe this is unnecessary. Even without a clear objective line we will be able to recognise circumstances in which we can agree the costs of alternatives are too high, situations in which the other options are unacceptable on any definition of unreasonable. As I think this is the case in what follows I will reserve further definition on this point. 9 Aside from the following criticism it is also worth noting that to think state coercion is justified by its positive consequences is not altogether plausible because it suffers the objection that if positive consequences are sufficient to justify coercion then almost any scheme of laws and redistribution can be considered just provided it improves on the state of nature. Journal of Global Ethics 10 affected by coercion that is of import. Rather, it is the concern that one’s life is structured in a particular way by the rules and this makes demands upon our will. We are asked to live with the social situation it places us in and uphold the laws even if we disagree with them. Because we are asked to bear this imposition we are entitled to demand equal justification. This is true regardless of the consequences of such imposition. The same mistake is made by Sangiovanni (2007, 13–14) with reference to non-voluntary rules. Sangiovanni thinks non- voluntary systems are necessary to preserve our autonomy and because of this beneficial consequence they do not require the same justification as coercion, but this is clearly false. If one has no reasonable exit option one must conform to rules and accept the social position in which they place her. In this sense, her will is still invoked by them and justification is still required. With these details clarified, we can now summarise Nagel’s argument on this view as follows: N3: It is only non-voluntary institutions that raise the particular positive demands of socio-economic justice. F3: Domestic institutions meet the criteria for issues of justice to arise – i.e. they are non-voluntary institutions – but international ones do not. C3: There is no justice beyond the state. This avoids the problems of aforementioned conceptions. In Country M the tyrant’s laws must be obeyed even though he is not authorised by the people and he does not claim a right to rule. We think his rules are unjust but the first step towards validating our opinion is verifying that matters of justice are at issue. The value of this conception is that it can achieve just that. N3, in other words, is plausible. Moreover, F3, under the specific definition of non-voluntariness adopted here, seems to correlate with some of Nagel’s assertions. Differentiating from minimum moral concerns, he states ‘political institutions are different because adherence to them is not voluntary’ and ‘[a]n institution that one has no choice about joining must offer terms of membership that meet a higher standard’ (Nagel 2005, 133). Arbitrary domestic inequalities and society’s laws are of special significance because we are bound ‘without being given a choice’ (Nagel 2005, 129). International institutions are different, Nagel continues, because, although they set forth rules, these agreements are just mutual self-interest bargains, controlled and financed by member states, attended by delegates representing separate states seeking to advance their own interests, and ‘mere economic interaction does not trigger the heightened standards of socioeconomic justice’ (Nagel 2005, 138). Nagel’s defence of F3, however, is unconvincing because there are international institutions, such as the World Trade Organisation (WTO), that are also non-voluntary. 10 This institution is attended by national delegates (amongst others) and its inception might 10 A similar point to this is acknowledged by Sangiovanni (2007, 18). However, Sangiovanni does very little beyond stating that the present international system is non-voluntary. While I agree with his point it will hardly suffice to refute Nagel’s thought that the present international system is voluntary. It merely begs the question. Here I will expand upon and prove the claim. It is also worth noting that as Sangiovanni says nothing to challenge the non-voluntariness conception normatively it is somewhat perplexing that he abandons it. To be sure, employing it does not allow him to draw his state-centric views about justice but this alone is no reason to discard the conception. If the view is normatively plausible then the conclusions that follow from it are those we should accept. Simply highlighting that as a view it leads to demands of global justice hardly qualifies as an objection to the view unless one assumes the conclusion that extra rempublicum nulla justitia. It is possible to deflect this criticism to a certain extent by providing a plausible alternative view that does restrict the scope of justice to the domestic realm. However, as noted above and as argued by Abizadeh (2008, 325-341, in particular 336-337), Sangiovanni fails to do even this. A. Walton 11 have relied on agreements between individual nations but it would be a mistake to think that it is now constituted by nothing more than a set of private contracts, established and easily revocable at state discretion. It now has a package of regulations and procedures that members must follow. To be sure, there is a formal right to withdraw but there is no genuine option to do so. The stigma associated with withdrawing and likely consequences for other areas of a state’s political and economic life would be far too high for us to consider this an ‘acceptable alternative’. This is evidenced by how much non-members are willing to sacrifice to join and by noting just how much relies on WTO membership in the present world. Given that members view each other as ‘most favoured nations’ any state that chooses to withdraw will lose its right to be treated non-discriminatorily which will mean not only an absolute decline in terms, and, therefore, gains, of trade but also a relative disadvantage, thus increasing the likelihood of losing trading agreements to others. Even aside from these direct costs, many, even the very wealthiest, have economies so ordered through WTO arrangements that this would cause structural chaos. Moreover, as it is so difficult to acquire International Monetary Fund and World Bank aid packages, or, for that matter, to gain much international credibility at all, without WTO affiliation a country can be confident of very little help with any troubles it faces. Its very existence, in other words, makes the option of being a non-member extremely costly; a point perhaps conclusively proven by the fact that despite continual complaints about WTO rules no state has ever even attempted to withdraw. It is hard to deny that membership is valuable and that there might be good reason to join voluntarily but this is true of many states. More importantly, the cost of non-membership is dramatic and if unacceptable costs are sufficient to deem domestic residence non-voluntary then inclusion in the world trade system qualifies too. In short, if what is important about authorities in matters of justice is that they establish non-voluntary frameworks then the condition is one that exists at the global level. There are three possible objections I can envisage to this. First, it could be suggested that I have exaggerated the non-voluntary nature of the WTO. That some states remain non- members shows, it could be argued, that the costs of being unattached are not sufficiently high to deem the option an unacceptable alternative. I do not think this objection succeeds, however, because the presence of non-conformers cannot substantiate this conclusion. In fact, they might be the exceptions that prove the rule. Let us examine this. To begin we can note that those that remain outside the system do suffer extreme consequences. North Korea is, for this as well as other reasons, in political exile while Turkmenistan’s economy is in dire straits (with unemployment and poverty figures both over 50%). These are costs which can surely be deemed excessive. If either country had succumbed to such pressures (or does so in the future) it would not be unreasonable to suggest that they had no genuine alternative. Even while they remain in dissent it would not be untenable to label their defiance as enduring costs greater than we would expect most to be able to bear. This would be sufficient then to maintain that those that remain in the system have no reasonable alternative to conformity and that their situation is non-voluntary in the relevant sense. There is nothing incoherent about this. There are people who violate laws and people who emigrate but this does not lead us to deem the state legal system is voluntary. Even when there is a full legal right of exit the idea still has application. Women within a legally gender neutral state who become housewives due to extreme social pressure are not usually thought to be acting voluntarily even if there are some who break the norm. For similar reasons, the existence of non-members should not lead us to think that alternatives to WTO membership are Journal of Global Ethics 12 reasonable or, accordingly, question the idea that it is a non-voluntary institution and a site of justice. 11 Second, it could be argued that although the WTO is a non-voluntary institution it is not analogous to the domestic state because it regulates only trade, whereas the latter establishes non-voluntary rules for many key areas of life. 12 This challenge, however, suffers a number of problems. If it is the thought that only trade is regulated in the international sphere then it ignores the plethora of global organisations that preside over at least as many areas of life as the domestic state. Alternatively then, it could be the thought that only trade is regulated by a non-voluntary institution and this is insufficient for issues of justice to arise. This idea would need supplementing by the (I think dubious) empirical claims that the WTO is the only non-voluntary international organisation and that it is an institution completely independent of others in the world order such that it should not be seen as the conformity- inducing branch of a broader scheme (because otherwise it would be hard to see the moral distinction between this and a government with an independent judiciary). However, let us set this problem aside and focus on the normative claim. This would appear to be the idea that the quantity of life-aspects regulated by an institution must be over a certain threshold for justice to be at issue, a concern perhaps motivated by the thought that institutions must have a significant impact for such matters to arise. This, however, is implausible, partly because it seems arbitrary, partly because the idea that the significance of impact must be beyond a certain level for it to raise moral concerns has been well refuted (Glover 1986), and partly because any qualification on the types of non-voluntary institutions that raise issues of justice will exclude scenarios in which we are certain justice is pertinent. If the Country M’s tyrant relinquished control over education would he thereby be excused the charge of injustice? Third, it is possible to suggest that the non-voluntariness of international institutions is not sufficient for issues of justice to arise between individuals worldwide because justice is only a concern between the individuals who are non-voluntarily implicated in the framework. For all that the WTO might be non-voluntary it is still only a structure for national representatives; it is not the collective framework of individuals. I am not sure how much this would show because even if the reasoning is valid it would still suggest there should be some concerns of justice within the ‘society of states’, which is more than Nagel wishes to accept. However, I do not think it can even achieve this much because we do not have any more genuine option to refuse conformity to the compacts agreed by our representatives than we do domestic laws. 13 Moreover, it is not merely that we are connected here through a third party. The laws passed down from the international system implicate us directly in a non- voluntary way. This is so in two respects. First, they are the product of a system which binds our governments who in turn bind us. That we have delegates interacting with the higher tier on our behalf does not sever the tie to our will because in this system these delegates merely become intermediaries through whom the rules are administered. There is, in other words, a transitive line of non-voluntary relationships between us and the global order: B (the state) is non-voluntarily bound by A (the global order); C (the individual) is non-voluntarily bound by B (the state); therefore C (the individual) is non-voluntarily bound by A (the global order). 11 One other possible consequence of acknowledging non-member states is that the argument above only suffices to show that there are concerns of justice between those involved in the WTO system and not those beyond. It might be necessary to accept this claim but it should be noted that even doing so will only restrict the scope of the claim to include fourteen less countries and two provinces. It should also be highlighted that this restriction would not apply to some of the other pillars of the international system, such as the UN. If we were to perceive the array of global institutions as one system (a basic structure with a number of parts) then there is no country that is not involved. 12 I thank Victor Tadros for bringing this concern to my attention. 13 This point I believe follows a line of reasoning similar to that of J. Cohen and C. Sabel. 2006. Extra Rempublicam Nulla Justitia? Philosophy and Public Affairs 34: 2: 147-175, pp. 166-168 A. Walton 13 Second, and perhaps more importantly, we are in one sense less free to extract ourselves from it. Given WTO laws pervade almost the entire planet, even if we could voluntarily leave our present country of residence we would be unlikely to escape them. We have almost literally no choice but to live under its rule. In short, if the arrangements bind us in the same non- voluntary way, both through the conformity of an authority which we must obey and directly, then they implicate our will by commanding conformity and they therefore raise issues of justice. Such then is Nagel’s dilemma. He can affirm N1 or N2 and face the charge that his understanding of the relationship between justice and authority is implausible. Alternatively he can accept the more plausible account given in N3 but he is then forced to accept that C3 is false because F3 is unsustainable. In other words, on any plausible reading of the relationship between authority and justice we must admit the latter applies at the global level. 4. Justice, Enforcement, and a Coercive World Order The point proffered in section three raises doubts over the second part of Nagel’s objection to global justice, but it may not be sufficient to refute his views for even with the engagement of citizen will it is possible the international system does not have other assets necessary for the issue to take hold. It may still remain hindered by Hobbes’ Dilemma. One could, that is, accept that the global order is unjust but argue, nonetheless, that without a sufficiently developed mechanism for guaranteeing obedience to the rules justice cannot be realised. This argument would read as follows: N4: Justice requires a method of collective enforcement to provide assurance of widespread conformity. F4: The domestic sovereign state can fulfil this role but present international institutions are not sufficiently powerful to do the same. C4: Global justice, even if a pertinent question, is a chimera. I am unsure whether N4 is sustainable. It is worth noting that states do not rely on coercive power alone to secure obedience and there are many examples of long-term cooperation achieved without force (consider the UK National Blood Service). As Caney notes, moreover, there are also alternative means of ensuring conformity (Caney 2005, 136- 139). On the other hand, it is certainly difficult to resist Hobbes’ thought because we have so often seen cooperation (especially in the name of justice) unravel due to the defection of only a few (consider the failures of the Kyoto Protocol). On many occasions no amount of noble motives on the part of some can bypass the obstinacy of others. This is what Ralph found in Lord of the Flies. However, we do not need to solve this puzzle because the above sequence fails regardless of N4’s validity. This is so for two reasons. First, even if we accept both the normative and factual premises C4 does not follow. This can be shown by simply stating a possible alternative conclusion, such as C4’: we should give our global institutions the power to enforce conformity. That there is no less logical consistency in N4-F4-C4’ shows that C4 is not a valid inference of the argument. If anything the latter seems the less obvious conclusion. Second, even aside from conceptual errors, the validity of the argument is questionable because F4 – the claim that there is no actor beyond the state with an enforcement mechanism – is empirically dubious. UN rules, for example, are backed by the legal recognition that sovereignty is violable if a state fails to meet its obligations. To be sure, the system is not perfect. The Security Council is renowned for its deficiencies and Journal of Global Ethics 14 there are numerous cases in which the system has failed to uphold the conventions. However, miscarriages of justice are not the same as there being no authority to enforce it. Not all domestic crimes are redressed (or even solved) but this does not imply the state should not be considered a coercive authority. In fact, that there was such outcry about the ineffectiveness of the Security Council in the delay over humanitarian intervention in, for instance, Rwanda, in part goes to show that the system is deemed to have some form of governance remit and is expected to enforce the rules. Perhaps this example will not convince some. Perhaps it will be argued that although the UN does have some enforcement criteria it does not have any enforcement capacity (its military forces are nothing more than assemblages of national armies at state discretion) and it can only “keep order” over weak states (not force powerful states to respect human rights (cf. Guantanamo Bay) or prevent unauthorised exercises of power (cf. the invasion of Iraq)). I am not convinced by these objections, not least because anomalies also arise in domestic states (such as riots or forms of political disobedience) and these do not raise doubt over the enduring capacity of the state system to enforce the law. Regardless, perhaps a more compelling example can be offered. On its gateway page it is stated that ‘the WTO’s procedure for resolving trade quarrels under the Dispute Settlement Understanding [(DSU)] is vital for enforcing the rules’ (WTO 2008). At this branch of the institution states can bring each other to account by filing reports against one another for not upholding WTO trade agreements. If the accused is found guilty it faces penalties for its transgressions. For example, the EC has faced heavy sanctions for its banana importation policy and its ban on hormone-fed beef (see WTO DS27 and WTO DS26 respectively). It has been widely used, seeing investigations of 181 disputes by July 2002, and it is worth noting that of the conclusions of these cases there has been ‘a successful implementation rate of 83%’ (Davey 2005, 46-47). This surely qualifies the WTO as a body with an enforcement mechanism. There are two objections I can envisage to this point. First, it might be claimed that this enforcement mechanism still remains a system implemented by the actions of states through interactional means of redress, not one involving higher powers. After all, the WTO notes that ‘ultimate responsibility for settling disputes...lies with member governments’ (WTO 2008). This poses little challenge though, because even if we accept that penalties within the system are enacted with one-to-one transactions it would not follow that they are not regulated by a higher authority. One could, in fact, imagine, in libertarian society for instance, a system of domestic law where the only major function of an arbitrating authority was to direct private actor disputes and recompense. Moreover, no matter how the WTO describes its operations it cannot be denied that final jurisdiction on disputes is the property of the institution’s panel. Second, one might claim that the DSU is merely a tool of the wealthy to enforce rulings on poorer states. I do not think this claim can be substantiated because although there are known complications with the DSU system for poorer states, some developing countries (notably India and Brazil) have made regular and effective use of it (Davey 2005, 40-45) and there have even been examples of David-Goliath type victories (cf. WTO DS285). Regardless, even if this objection could be substantiated it would only reinforce my argument: that injustice can be imposed upon some (the essential complaint) shows that the system has the capacity to enforce conformity, and, therefore, that it can do so fairly if so directed. In short, even accepting N4 we have good reason to doubt F4 and even accepting N4 and F4 we have good reason to doubt C4. We can only conclude, therefore, either that the world order has the capacities necessary to enforce justice or that we should enable it such. On neither account is there reason to believe that the idea of global justice lacks application. A. Walton 15 Conclusion Nagel argues that global justice is not pertinent in the present world because it is an issue only raised by a unique authority relation and possible only in the presence of an enforcement mechanism. The moral foundations of his view will be disputed by some. Such objection, however, may not even be necessary. In this paper I have shown that even if we accept his broad normative claim his conclusions are invalid because the two necessary conditions he cites for issues of justice to arise exist in the contemporary world order. We have, that is, a global system sufficiently developed to raise and (at least potentially) administer questions of justice even on an institutional conception. Acknowledgments I thank audiences at the Warwick Critical and International Studies Working Group and the Warwick Centre for Ethics, Law and Public Affairs for their comments on earlier drafts of this paper, and in particular Dominic Kelly, Victor Tadros and Edward Page for their inputs. I am especially grateful to Matthew Clayton for extensive feedback and discussion in the development of this paper. I also thank my two referees at the Journal of Global Ethics, David Stevens and Ronald Tinnevelt, for their suggestions and comments on how it needed improving. Reference List Abizadeh, A. 2007. Cooperation, Pervasive Impact, and Coercion: On the Scope (not Site) of Distributive Justice. Philosophy and Public Affairs 35: 4: 318-358. Beitz, C. 1999. Political Theory and International Relations. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Blake, M. 2001. Distributive Justice, State Coercion, and Autonomy. Philosophy and Public Affairs. 30: 3: 257-296. Caney, S. 2005. Justice Beyond Borders: A Global Political Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Caney, S. 2008. Global Distributive Justice and the State. Political Studies 56: 3: 487-518. Cohen, J., and Sabel, C. 2006. Extra Rempublicam Nulla Justitia? Philosophy and Public Affairs 34: 2: 147-175. Davey, W.J. 2005. The WTO Dispute Settlement System: The First Ten Years. Journal of International Economic Law 8: 1: 17-50. Glover, J. 1986. ‘It Makes No Difference Whether or Not I Do It’. In Applied Ethics, ed. P. Singer, 125-144. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hume, D. 1777. Essays: Moral, Political, and Literary. E.F. Miller, ed. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund, 1985. Journal of Global Ethics 16 Julius, A.J. 2006. Nagel’s Atlas. Philosophy and Public Affairs 34: 2: 176-192. Martin, R. 2006. Rawls on International Distributive Economic Justice: Taking a Closer Look. In Rawls’s Law of Peoples: A Realistic Utopia?, eds. R. Martin and D.A. Reidy, 226- 242. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Nagel, T. 2005. The Problem of Global Justice. Philosophy and Public Affairs 33: 2: 113- 147. Olsaretti, S. 2004. Liberty, Desert and the Market: A Philosophical Study. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Pevnick, R. 2008. Political Coercion and the Scope of Distributive Justice. Political Studies 56: 2: 399-413. Pogge, T. 1989. Realizing Rawls. London/Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Pogge, T. 2006. Do Rawls’s Two Theories of Justice Fit Together? In Rawls’s Law of Peoples: A Realistic Utopia?, eds. R. Martin and D.A. Reidy, 206-225. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Rawls, J. 1999a. A Theory of Justice (Revised Edition). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Rawls, J. 1999b. The Law of Peoples. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. Rawls, J. 2005. Political Liberalism (Expanded Edition). New York: Columbia University Press. Raz, J. 1986. The Morality of Freedom. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Raz, J. 1990. Introduction. In Authority, ed. J. Raz, 1-19. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Raz, J. 1990. Practical Reason and Norms. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Sangiovanni, A. 2007. Global Justice, Reciprocity, and the State. Philosophy and Public Affairs 35: 1: 3-39. Singer, P. 2002. One World: The Ethics of Globalization. New Haven: Yale University Press. Steiner, H. 1994. An Essay on Rights. Oxford: Blackwell. Williams, A. 1998. Incentives, Inequality and Publicity. Philosophy and Public Affairs 27: 3: 225-247. World Trade Organisation. 2008. Dispute Settlement. Available at http://www.wto.org/english/tratop_e/dispu_e/dispu_e.htm http://www.wto.org/english/tratop_e/dispu_e/dispu_e.htm A. Walton 17 World Trade Organisation. Dispute DS26: European Communities – Measures Concerning Meat and Meat Products (Hormones). Available at http://www.wto.org/english/tratop_e/dispu_e/cases_e/ds26_e.htm World Trade Organisation. Dispute DS27: European Communities – Regime for the Importation, Sale and Distribution of Bananas. Available at http://www.wto.org/english/tratop_e/dispu_e/cases_e/ds27_e.htm World Trade Organisation. Dispute DS285: United States – Measures Affecting the Cross- Border Supply of Gambling and Betting Services. Available at http://www.wto.org/english/tratop_e/dispu_e/cases_e/ds285_e.htm http://www.wto.org/english/tratop_e/dispu_e/cases_e/ds26_e.htm http://www.wto.org/english/tratop_e/dispu_e/cases_e/ds27_e.htm http://www.wto.org/english/tratop_e/dispu_e/cases_e/ds285_e.htm work_c65pbgivdrfhzg7npqdqh77sku ---- Microsoft Word - 12A_teubner_uk.doc European Journal of Legal Studies Special Conference Issue: “Governance, Civil Society and Social Movements” Edited jointly by Michael Blecher, Giuseppe Bronzini, Jennifer Hendry, Christian Joerges and the EJLS Justice Under Global Capitalism? Gunther Teubner VOLUME 1 NUMBER 3 2008 P. 1-8 1 Justice Under Global Capitalism? Gunther Teubner * Double Diagnosis: Clash of Rationalities, Re-socialisation of Conflicts Globalised capitalism cannot be understood as being driven by economic processes alone. The alternative to conventional ideas of an economy-led form of globalisation is “polycentric globalisation”. The primary motor is an accelerated differentiation of society into autonomous social systems, each of which expands beyond territorial boundaries and constitutes itself globally. This process is not confined to markets alone but also encompasses science, culture, technology, health, the military, transport, tourism and sport, as well as, albeit in a clearly more restricted form, politics, law and welfare. 1 When describing the external relations between these global villages, the term “clash of cultures” is appropriate. Through their own operative closure, global functional systems are free to intensify their own rationality without regard to other social systems or, indeed, regard * Johann-Wolfgang von Goethe Universität, Frankfurt 1 Various social theories on legal globalisation make this point: on theories of global culture see, for example, J.W. Meyer, J. Boli, G.M. Thomas and F.O. Ramirez, “World Society and the Nation-State”, in American Journal of Sociology 103/144 (1997); on discourse analysis, see A. Schütz, “The Twilight of the Global Polis: On Losing Paradigms, Environing Systems, and Observing World Society”, in G. Teubner, ed., Global Law Without A State, 257ff; on global legal pluralism, see B. de Sousa Santos, Toward A ew Legal Common Sense: Law, Globalisation & Emancipation (London: Butterworths, LexisNexis, 2003) passim; on global civil society, see D. Held, Democracy and the Global Order: From the Modern State to Cosmopolitan Governance (Cambridge: Polity, 1995), passim; on world society, see the contributions in M. Albert & L. Hilkermeier, eds., Observing International Relations. iklas Luhmann and World Politics (London, New York: Routledge, 2004) 2 for their natural or human environment. Ever since the pioneering analysis of Karl Marx, repeated proof has been provided as to the destructive potential of a globalised economic rationality. Max Weber deployed the concept of modern polytheism in his efforts to identify this potential within other areas of life, and to analyse the resulting (and threatening) rationality conflicts that can arise. In the meantime, the human and ecological risks posed by other highly specialised global systems, such as science and technology, have also become readily apparent to a far broader public. Similarly, and especially where the position of countries within the southern hemisphere is considered, it is clear that real dangers are posed less by the dynamics of international politics and more by economic, scientific and technological rationality spheres that instigate a “clash of rationalities”. In Niklas Luhmann’s central thesis, the underlying cause for post-modern risks is to be found within the rationality maximisation that different globally active functional systems are engaged in, which hides an enormous potential for endangering people, nature and society. 2 Problems raised by global finance markets, hedge funds, financial speculation, pharmaceutical patents, drugs trade, and reproductive cloning, for example, are caused by the fragmented and operationally closed functional systems of a global society in all their expansionist fervour. A reversal, or a turn towards the de-differentiation of society and a resurrection of old myths, is also excluded if the civilising achievements of this highly ambivalent development are to be retained: ‘[T]he sin of differentiation can never be undone. Paradise is lost.’ 3 In the eighties of the last century, Habermas diagnosed a conspicuous trend in the crisis of late capitalism: explosive social conflicts have been moved from the private markets to the welfare 2 N. Luhmann, Die Gesellschaft der Gesellschaft, (Frankfurt/M: Suhrkamp, 1997), at 1088 et seq. 3 N. Luhamnn, Die Wirtschaft der Gesellschaft (Frankfurt/M: Suhrkamp, 1994), at 344. 3 state institutions. 4 Today we can observe a reversal of this trend: explosive political conflicts that were formerly absorbed within the diverse regimes of the welfare state do not vanish after privatisation; rather, after the take-over by the market, these conflicting energies move back from welfare state institutions to private markets and re-emerge there in new forms. It is now the new private regimes of governance that have to cope with them, but they cannot be resolved by market mechanisms. As a result, privatised activities will be driven into a new politicisation. This re-politicisation is not necessarily limited to the establishment of public law regulatory agencies, however, but also entails the politicisation of private governance itself, its different modes of self-regulation and conflict resolution via private litigation. The sources of this conflict can be identified in those privatised activities that have to bear the clash of rationalities themselves, the structural tensions between their proper rationality and economic calculation – professionals as well as clients suffer from those tensions. Here, in the resistance of social practices to their new economic regime, is the source of all kinds of new quasi- political conflicts, which now take place within the “private” spheres. 5 A good indicator for this change is the growing intensity of political fights between regulatory agencies, consumer groups, regulated companies and their shareholders that we are presently witnessing, and the extent to which protest movements and other forms of civic resistance are switching their targets from political to economic institutions. There is also the strange alliance between civic 4 J. Habermas, Legitimation Crisis (Cambridge, UK: Polity, 1975) 5 For what these changes mean for private law, see G. Teubner, “In the Blind Spot: The Hybridization of Contracting” (2007) Theoretical Inquiries in Law 1/4/8, at 51-71; G. Teubner, “Global Private Regimes: Neo- spontaneous Law and Dual Constitution of Autonomous Sectors?” in K-H. Ladeur, ed., Public Governance in an Age of Globalisation (Aldershot: Ashgate, 2004); Gunther Teubner, “Contracting Worlds: Invoking Discourse Rights in Private Governance Regimes”, Social and Legal Studies 9 (2000) at 399-417 4 protest movements and mass media speaking up in the name of ethics against a comprehensive economisation of activities which damages their integrity. Social and Legal Counter-Movements Societal constitutionalism is not limited to a tendency within the law; rather, it designates a series of social counter-movements directed against the destructive aspects of functional differentiation. These counter-movements coerce expansive social systems to self-restriction. 6 In particular, fundamental rights are not just judicially protected rights of individuals against state power as lawyers usually see them, but are much broader social counter-institutions that, after long-term conflicts, emerge inside expansive social sub-systems and serve to restrict this expansion from within. Historically, basic rights have emerged in reaction to the emergence of autonomous spheres of action in modern society, especially in response to the matrix of autonomised politics. As soon as expansionist tendencies that threatened the integrity of other autonomous areas of society became evident in politics, turbulent social conflicts ensued. Expansionist tendencies have manifested themselves historically in very different constellations; in the past, mainly in politics but today, mainly in economics, science, technology and other sectors of society. If the core task of political basic rights was to protect the autonomy of spheres of action from political instrumentalisation, then the central task of 6 For details see, G. Teubner, “The Anonymous Matrix: Human Rights Violations by ‘Private’ Transnational Actors” in Modern Law Review 69 (2006) at 327-346; see also G. Verschraegen, “Human Rights and Modern Society: A Sociological Analysis from the Perspective of Systems Theory” Journal of Law and Society 29 (2002) at 258-281; K-H. Ladeur, “Helmut Ridders Konzeption der Meinungs- und Pressefreiheit in der Demokratie” in Kritische Justiz 32 (1999) at 281-300; C. Graber and G. Teubner, “Art and Money: Constitutional Rights in the Private Sphere” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 18 (1998) at 61-74 5 “social basic rights” has become to make it possible to safeguard so-called non-rational action logic against the matrix of the dominant social trends towards rationalisation. 7 Human rights, therefore, cannot be limited to the relation between State and individual, or the area of institutionalised politics, or even solely to phenomena of power in the broadest sense. Specific endangerment of physical and mental integrity by a communicative matrix comes not just from politics but, in principle, from all social sectors that have expansive tendencies. For the matrix of the economy, Marx clarified this particularly through such concepts as alienation, autonomy of capital, commodification of the world, exploitation of man by man. Today we see – most clearly in the writings of Foucault, Agamben, and Legendre – similar threats to human 7 This is the core idea of societal constitutionalism developed by D. Sciulli in his Theory of Societal Constitutionalism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992) at 21 ff.; see also D. Sciulli, Corporate Power in Civil Society: An Application of Societal Constitutionalism (New York: New York University Press, 2001) at 131 ff. For an elaboration, G. Teubner, “Societal Constitutionalism: Alternatives to State-centred Constitutional theory?” in C. Joerges, I-J. Sand and G. Teubner, eds., Constitutionalism and Transnational Governance (Oxford: Hart, 2004), 3-28. For the related concept of constitutional pluralism beyond the nation state, see N. Walker, "The Idea of Constitutional Pluralism", 65 Modern Law Review 65 (2002) 317-359 and N. Walker, “Taking Constitutionalism Beyond the State”, RECON Online Working Papers (2007)1-18; C. Walter, “Constitutionalizing (Inter)national Governance: Possibilities for and Limits to the Development of an International Constitutional Law”, German Yearbook of International Law 44 (2001) 170-201; H. Schepel, The Constitution of Private Governance: Product Standards in the Regulation of Integrating Markets, (Oxford: Hart, 2005), 161 ff.; For a parallel diagnosis in the “new economic constitutionalism”, see J. Tully, “The Imperialism of Modern Constitutional Democracy”, in N. Walker & M. Loughlin, eds., The Paradox of Constitutionalism: Constituent Power and Constitutional Form (Oxford: OUP, 2007) 315-338 6 integrity from the matrices of the natural science, of psychology, the social sciences, technology, medicine, the press, radio, television, and telecommunications. 8 The human rights question in the strictest sense must today be seen as a response to the endangerment of individuals’ integrity of body and mind by a multiplicity of anonymous and globalised communicative processes. It now becomes clear how a new “equation” replaces the old “equation” of the horizontal effect. The old one was based on a relation between two private actors – private perpetrator and private victim of the infringement. Now, in the new equation, one side is no longer a private actor as the fundamental rights violator, but rather the anonymous matrix of an autonomised communicative medium. Similarly, the other side is no longer simply the compact individual – now on this side of the equation the fundamental rights have to be systematically divided into three dimensions: - Institutional rights protecting the autonomy of social discourses – the autonomy of art, of science, of religion – against their subjugation by the totalising tendencies of the communicative matrix. By protecting social discourses against the totalitarian tendencies of science, media or economy, fundamental rights take effect as “conflict of law rules” between partial rationalities in society. - Personal rights protecting the autonomy of communications, attributed not to institutions, but to the social artefacts called “persons”. - Human rights as negative bounds on societal communication, where the integrity of individuals’ body and mind is endangered by a communicative matrix that crosses boundaries. 8 G. Agamben, Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998), 15 et seq.; M. Foucault, Discipline & Punish: The Birth of the Prison, (London: Penguin Books, 1991); P. Legendre, Leçons VIII. Le crime du caporal Lortie. Traité sur le père (Paris: Fayard, 1989) 7 However, even after such a reformulation of the human rights concept, the nagging question remains: can one discourse do justice to the other? This is a problem the dilemmas of which have been analysed by Lyotard, 9 but it is at least a problem within society, one Luhmann sought to respond to with the concept of justice as socially adequate complexity. 10 The situation is still more dramatic in terms of human rights in the strict sense, located as they are at the boundary between communication and the individual human being. All the groping attempts to juridify human rights cannot hide the fact that this is a strictly impossible project. How can society ever “do justice” to real people if people are not its parts but stand outside communication, if society cannot communicate with them but at most about them, indeed not even reach them but merely either irritate or destroy them? In the light of grossly inhuman social practices, the justice of human rights is a burning issue, but one which has no prospect of resolution. This has to be said in all rigour. If a positive concept of justice in the relation between communication and human beings is definitively impossible, then what is left, if we are not to succumb to post-structuralist quietism, is only second best. In the law, we have to accept that the problem of the integrity of body and mind can only be experienced through the inadequate sensors of irritation, reconstruction and re-entry. The deep dimension of conflicts between communication, on the one hand, and mind and body on the other, can at best be surmised by law. The only signpost left is legal prohibition, through which a self-limitation of communication seems possible, but even this prohibition can only describe the transcendence of the other allegorically. This 9 J-F Lyotard, The Differend: Phrases in Dispute (Manchester: Manchester Univ. Press, 1988), cif. 1 et seq. 10 N. Luhmann, Rechtssystem und Rechtsdogmatik (Stuttgart: Kohlhammer, 1974); N. Luhmann, Ausdifferenzierung des Rechts: Beiträge zur Rechtssoziologie und Rechtstheorie, (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1981) 374 et seq. 8 programme of justice is ultimately doomed to fail, and cannot, with Derrida, just console itself that it is “to come, à venir”, 11 but it has to face up its being, in principle, impossible. The justice of human rights can, then, at best be formulated negatively. It is aimed at removing unjust situations, not creating just ones. It is only the counter-principle to communicative violations of body and soul, a protest against inhumanities of communication, without it ever being possible to say positively what the conditions of humanly just communication might be. 11 J. Derrida, “Force of Law: The Mystical Foundation of Authority”, Cardozo Law Review 11 (1990) 919 et seq., at 969. work_c7jpr6l5sbd7nk2kkiq7hfwzci ---- None work_c7spfsgo2nf3ncqs6bucnj6xcy ---- Justice Reinvestment: Vision and Practice CR03CH15_Sabol ARjats.cls December 3, 2019 16:39 Annual Review of Criminology Justice Reinvestment: Vision and Practice William J. Sabol and Miranda L. Baumann Andrew Young School of Policy Studies, Department of Criminal Justice and Criminology, Georgia State University, Atlanta, Georgia 30303, USA; email: wsabol@gsu.edu Annu. Rev. Criminol. 2020. 3:317–39 First published as a Review in Advance on October 7, 2019 The Annual Review of Criminology is online at criminol.annualreviews.org https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-criminol-011419- 041407 Copyright © 2020 by Annual Reviews. All rights reserved Keywords reinvestment, community, corrections, cost efficiency, public safety, incarceration Abstract Justice reinvestment was introduced in the early 2000s as a means to respond to the massive growth in incarceration in the United States that had oc- curred during the past three decades by diverting offenders from prison and redirecting a portion of the associated corrections expenditures into com- munities to build their capacities to manage offenders locally. Over the next 17 years, the concept evolved into a Congressionally funded federal grant program that shifted the focus of reinvestment away from community rein- vestment and toward a state-agency practice improvement model that ulti- mately aimed to improve public safety. A distinct form of justice reinvest- ment, the Justice Reinvestment Initiative ( JRI), was the dominant practice of justice reinvestment in the United States. It was organized as a public– private partnership that engaged states in bipartisan efforts to enact leg- islative reforms and other policies to address sentencing and corrections practices and adopt high-performing evidence-based practices (EBPs) that would yield the desired public safety benefits. JRI contributed to legislative reforms and adoption of EBPs, especially in community supervision. The federal JRI effort has not yet provided peer-reviewed, published evidence that it has achieved its objectives. 317 A nn u. R ev . C ri m in ol . 2 02 0. 3: 31 7- 33 9. D ow nl oa de d fr om w w w .a nn ua lr ev ie w s. or g A cc es s pr ov id ed b y C ar ne gi e M el lo n U ni ve rs it y on 0 4/ 05 /2 1. F or p er so na l us e on ly . mailto:wsabol@gsu.edu https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-criminol-011419-041407 https://www.annualreviews.org/doi/full/10.1146/annurev-criminol-011419-041407 CR03CH15_Sabol ARjats.cls December 3, 2019 16:39 INTRODUCTION When Susan Tucker and Eric Cadora introduced the concept of justice reinvestment in 2003 (Tucker & Cadora 2003), the prison population in the United States had increased from approxi- mately 200,000 persons in the early 1970s to 1.3 million persons. It would continue to rise to ap- proximately 1.6 million around 2007, before beginning a slow decline (Bronson & Carson 2019, Carson 2018). Calling this expansion of incarceration a costly national dependence on a penal policy that sacrificed rather than enhanced public safety, they proposed that public safety could be improved by reducing the size and costs of correctional populations, redirecting a portion of the cost savings toward investments in local communities, and “devolving accountability and re- sponsibility to the local level” (Tucker & Cadora 2003, p. 2). Under their model, locally directed investment in education, jobs, housing, healthcare, and other community amenities would en- hance or rebuild communities, thereby leading to less crime and less incarceration. Locally based supervision of offenders would improve the accountability of local justice agencies and offenders, lower costs, and facilitate offender integration into communities. Over the next 15 years, the concept of justice reinvestment evolved, obtained the support of private foundations, was adopted internationally, and resulted in more than $160 million in federal investment in the United States. It has been described as “the largest effort within the United States—and now in other Western nations—to reverse what many have lamented as the use of mass incarceration” (Austin & Coventry 2014, p. 127); presented as providing a viable solution to the problem of increasing corrections expenditures and “dissatisfaction with current returns on public safety investment[s]” (La Vigne et al. 2014, p. 7); and credited with widespread adoption of evidence-based corrections programs (Klingele 2015). The Justice Reinvestment Initiative, or JRI, a public–private partnership between the Bureau of Justice Assistance (BJA) and the Pew Charitable Trusts (Pew), was the main form of justice rein- vestment in the United States. It shifted the focus of reinvestment from individual communities to managing costs and legislating reforms that would improve the efficiency of criminal justice system operations as a means to reduce recidivism and improve public safety. At least 35 states participated in some form of justice reinvestment between 2007 and 2017 (Pew 2018), and many were pro- jected to have or were credited with having smaller prison populations than would have occurred in the absence of JRI reforms. Collectively, the states were projected to avert billions of dollars in corrections costs over periods as long as 11 years (Harvell et al. 2017, LaVigne et al. 2014). Nongovernmental entities such as the Council of State Governments (CSG) and Pew, who also provided technical assistance (TA) to JRI participants, and the Urban Institute, which was re- sponsible for assessing outcomes and impacts of JRI, have tracked and recorded many examples of JRI efforts in states and localities. Each has devoted space on their respective website [Council of State Governments (https://www.csg.org/), Pew (https://www.pewresearch.org/), Urban In- stitute (https://www.urban.org)] to justice reinvestment, with literally hundreds of articles, fact sheets, reports, and stories, mostly touting successful reinvestment efforts, sharing lessons learned, or otherwise promoting the value of JRI. However, independent reviews of justice reinvestment have been limited and largely critical. Two books (Brown et al. 2016, Fox et al. 2013) reviewed justice reinvestment in the United States, the United Kingdom, and Australia. Both argued that it was a major movement in criminal justice reform that could be used to reduce crime through investment in social justice (Fox et al. 2013), had the potential to create a new dialog about how to reduce incarceration and the racial disparities within it, and build community capacity (Brown et al. 2016). Both concluded that it had not yet achieved its goals. A special edition of Criminology & Public Policy devoted to mass incarceration included a proposal for justice reinvestment and a set of commentaries that generally were less 318 Sabol • Baumann A nn u. R ev . C ri m in ol . 2 02 0. 3: 31 7- 33 9. D ow nl oa de d fr om w w w .a nn ua lr ev ie w s. or g A cc es s pr ov id ed b y C ar ne gi e M el lo n U ni ve rs it y on 0 4/ 05 /2 1. F or p er so na l us e on ly . https://www.csg.org/ https://www.pewresearch.org/ https://www.urban.org CR03CH15_Sabol ARjats.cls December 3, 2019 16:39 sanguine about its prospects than the books. Assessments of it within the broader contexts of the politics of mass incarceration (Gottschalk 2015), the economics of prison growth (Pfaff 2016), sentencing reform of the 2000s (O’Hear 2017), and community supervision practices (Klingele 2015) have pointed out some of its internal contradictions. Finally, despite its scope and the public attention given to justice reinvestment, it was not given a prominent place in either of two recently published volumes devoted to criminal justice reform. Neither Erik Luna’s four-volume Reforming Criminal Justice (Luna 2017a) nor Michael Tonry & Daniel Nagin’s Reinventing American Criminal Justice (Tonry & Nagin 2017) devoted a chapter to it, although several of the papers in Luna’s volumes gave it limited attention in their discussions of prison or supervision reform efforts. Our review distinguishes between the concepts of justice reinvestment, which allows for justice funds to be reallocated to non-justice domains, and the JRI, which characterized the US experi- ence. We describe the justice reinvestment concept as originally envisioned and how it evolved, particularly within the United States. We describe the transition from justice reinvestment to JRI, which represented a marked shift in the emphasis of reinvestment away from place- and community-based offender management to a state-level strategy that emphasized improving cor- rections departments’ practices through expanded use of evidence-based programming. This shift largely preserved the size and oversight function of the justice system, as reinvested dollars flowed from one sector of the justice system to another, as opposed to community-based, primary preven- tion efforts. Our review therefore focuses largely on the JRI experience and the extent to which it achieved its objectives. We conclude with observations about both justice reinvestment and JRI. ORIGINS AND EVOLUTION OF THE CONCEPT OF JUSTICE REINVESTMENT The theoretical basis for justice reinvestment comes from the community development literature, but it borrows insights from research on the collateral consequences of incarceration. Individual-, community-, and system-level characteristics were seen as inextricably linked causes of crime that necessitated multipronged reforms to address. First, justice reinvestment’s systems-level approach sought to ameliorate the impact of concentrated mass incarceration and coercive mobility—the forced removal and return of community residents through incarceration (Clear et al. 2003)—by reforming sentencing and revocation policies to reduce the use of prison (Austin et al. 2013, Clear 2011, Tucker & Cadora 2003). Second, justice reinvestment emphasized the importance of bol- stering family and community cohesion through the adoption of policies designed to revitalize distressed communities and increase the availability of preventive programs and educational and economic opportunities (Clear 2011, Tucker & Cadora 2003). Finally, justice reinvestment em- phasized assessment of offenders to address their individual treatment and programmatic needs while also managing their public safety risk (Clear 2011). This also exhibited itself in the concept of local community control and accountability for offenders. Tucker & Cadora (2003) viewed justice reinvestment as a means to reduce mass incarcera- tion and build capacity in communities affected by it. They located the causes of mass incarcera- tion in the tough sentencing and corrections policies of the 1980s and 1990s, such as the war on drugs, mandatory minimums, three-strike sentences, truth-in-sentencing, and diminution of ju- dicial discretion. Pointing to findings that a relatively small number of neighborhoods accounted for a disproportionately high number of prison admissions (Clear 2008, Clear et al. 2003, Kurgan 2013, Lynch & Sabol 2001, Sampson & Loeffler 2010), Tucker & Cadora dubbed as million-dollar blocks those areas associated with massive corrections expenditures that have also struggled with pervasive crime despite record-high levels of incarceration. And they asked if some portion of those costs might not be put to different uses that would strengthen communities. www.annualreviews.org • Justice Reinvestment 319 A nn u. R ev . C ri m in ol . 2 02 0. 3: 31 7- 33 9. D ow nl oa de d fr om w w w .a nn ua lr ev ie w s. or g A cc es s pr ov id ed b y C ar ne gi e M el lo n U ni ve rs it y on 0 4/ 05 /2 1. F or p er so na l us e on ly . CR03CH15_Sabol ARjats.cls December 3, 2019 16:39 Following the arguments of Clear et al. (2003), Tucker & Cadora argued that high rates of removal of residents to incarceration introduced coercive mobility, which diminished informal social control in communities that, in turn, led to more crime. Offenders’ opportunities for suc- cess were limited by high rates of reincarceration for technical violations while on parole, a dearth of training and treatment services available upon reentry, and the fragility of economic and social institutions in the neighborhoods to which they were returning. Opportunities for offender rein- tegration were exacerbated by the lack of programmatic, economic, and social support systems within the neighborhoods with high concentrations of crime and incarceration. Under justice reinvestment, some of the monies that would have gone to cover the costs of imprisonment would flow from the state to local communities to manage offenders locally and invest in community institutions. Localities would be accountable to the state for any person who reoffends and goes to state prison. Locally tailored solutions would include, for example, allocating parole officers to neighborhoods rather than dispersing their workloads; designing prisoner reen- try as a shared responsibility of governments, community institutions, families and friends, and the individual offender; and building communities through reinvestments targeted at improving local schools, housing, employment, and other objectives. Eight years after Tucker & Cadora, Todd Clear (2011) proposed a justice reinvestment model for a place-based, detailed voucher system that diverted cost savings from states’ corrections budgets to community-based organizations and employers on a per-offender, real-time basis. Approved organizations and employers who treated or employed diverted offenders in specific, high-incarceration communities would receive monthly subsidies so long as the offenders did not reoffend or become reincarcerated. Clear built local accountability into the model by eliminating the state subsidy for cases of supervised offenders reoffending for a new crime. To ensure emphasis on community revitalization and sustainability, the model required participating organizations to employ offenders and their families and provide key services, such as housing, educational or vocational training, and substance-abuse treatment. This original vision of justice reinvestment was met with a mixture of praise and skepticism. On one hand, the concept was characterized by the “elegance of the critique and solution” as an “aesthetically compelling idea” that gives “pleasure to the mind or senses,” and had properties of “harmony of form or color, excellence of artistry, truthfulness, and originality” that policy makers and art galleries seek to find (Maruna 2011,pp.661–62).It was described as an approach that would have broad appeal because it could provide “greater safety for citizens through redeploying some of the wasteful sums needlessly spent on imprisonment” (Allen 2011, p. 617). The National Re- search Council (NRC) offered that JRI could contribute to the neighborhood capacity building of the initial justice reinvestment efforts as part of an approach to “reduc[e] reliance on incar- ceration” (Travis et al. 2014, p. 353). Klingele (2015) expressed hopefulness that JRI’s pragmatic approach could continue to bring political partisans together in a way that would potentially lead to more reform. On the other hand, criticisms of the original concept of justice reinvestment pointed out that the concept was not fully developed and did not address important issues. First and foremost, justice reinvestment did not address the assumptions that sufficient funds could be diverted for community reinvestment and the mechanisms by which funding streams for community rein- vestment would be sustained if prison costs decreased were not articulated. Questioning whether the savings that could be extracted from corrections would be sufficient without first obtaining very large reductions in the size of prison populations, Austin (2011, Austin et al. 2013) called for sentencing reforms that would curb admissions for new crimes and shorten lengths of stay. Their justice reinvestment proposals included reclassifying certain crimes as misdemeanors, re- ducing arrests for drug offenses, expanding early release eligibility for most offenders, imposing 320 Sabol • Baumann A nn u. R ev . C ri m in ol . 2 02 0. 3: 31 7- 33 9. D ow nl oa de d fr om w w w .a nn ua lr ev ie w s. or g A cc es s pr ov id ed b y C ar ne gi e M el lo n U ni ve rs it y on 0 4/ 05 /2 1. F or p er so na l us e on ly . CR03CH15_Sabol ARjats.cls December 3, 2019 16:39 shorter terms for many crimes, and eliminating mandatory minimums and life sentences for most crimes. If implemented, these would lead to much smaller prison populations and possibly greater amounts for reinvestment. Their model also required local municipal and county officials to act in coalitions to press for reforms that would reduce the concentration of incarceration in their communities as well as share in the political risks of legislating the reforms that reduced reliance on incarceration. But even under the more radical approach preferred by Austin et al. (2013), it is not clear that there would be sufficient savings for community reinvestment. Kleiman (2011) estimated that if the prison population were halved and coupled with the necessary expansion of treatment services for offenders diverted to supervision, approximately $10 billion in savings on the $50 billion spent by states would occur. This amounted to approximately half of one percent of state expenditures, an amount that seems inadequate to address the community reinvestment needs. Furthermore, state legislatures appropriate funds, not averted costs or savings. It is therefore far from certain that state legislatures would appropriate the savings for local community reinvestment as opposed to other needs (Tonry 2011). Even under Clear’s voucher model, it is not clear where state prison departments would get funding to pay the vouchers if their prison populations were reduced. More likely, state legislatures would appropriate smaller amounts for state prison departments under such a scenario. Furthermore,the cost savings associated with reducing prison populations were generally over- stated (Gottschalk 2015, Pfaff 2016, Tonry 2011). Estimates of savings based on per-capita or av- erage costs per prisoner overstate the savings unless entire prisons are shut down. This is because most prison costs are fixed costs for personnel, operations, and amortization. These costs do not change without substantial reductions in the number of facilities and number of staff. The means by which states would implement reductions in force if significant prison population reductions occurred also were not addressed (Gottschalk 2015). Additionally, justice reinvestment advocates did not address the potential for increasing in- equities and disparities in resources, services, and the administration of justice that could arise from devolving authority to localities (Allen 2011). These pragmatic appeals to instrumental ar- guments about costs and benefits ignored the severity of sentencing in the United States (Maruna 2011, Mayer & Patti 2015, Tonry 2011). Early Justice Reinvestment Implementation Efforts Between 2004 and 2008, Connecticut, Kansas, Texas, Rhode Island, and Arizona initiated justice reinvestment efforts (Austin & Coventry 2014). With financial support from the Open Society Foundations and later Pew, and with the TA from nonprofit research and TA firms, including the JFA Institute, CSG, and other organizations, the original justice reinvestment strategy was orga- nized around three parts: working with state legislatures to analyze criminal justice populations to recommend ways to generate savings; engaging experts to steer investment opportunities; and organizing demand for neighborhood investment by affected communities (Austin et al. 2013). Fox et al. (2013) and Brown et al. (2016) describe several of these early efforts. Most led to a variety of policy reforms that targeted administrative practices such as reducing revocations for technical violations of parole and probation, reestablishing good-time credits to reduce lengths of stay in prison, and holding parole hearings at the earliest possible date. Connecticut, Kansas, and Texas also expanded their community-based treatment and supervision practices in an effort to increase the use of alternative sanctions and provide greater reentry services. In at least three states, some form of community reinvestment was attempted. Texas reallocated several million dollars from its reserves to expand its Nurse–Family Partnership program—an www.annualreviews.org • Justice Reinvestment 321 A nn u. R ev . C ri m in ol . 2 02 0. 3: 31 7- 33 9. D ow nl oa de d fr om w w w .a nn ua lr ev ie w s. or g A cc es s pr ov id ed b y C ar ne gi e M el lo n U ni ve rs it y on 0 4/ 05 /2 1. F or p er so na l us e on ly . CR03CH15_Sabol ARjats.cls December 3, 2019 16:39 effort to reduce violence and improve the health and well-being of low-income families (Clement et al. 2011). Connecticut outlined a plan to reinvest correctional savings, along with private in- vestments and federal grants,to bolster employment opportunities in the state’s high-incarceration communities (CSG 2003). Eventually, Connecticut invested in transitional housing for returning inmates (Austin et al. 2013). In 2007, Kansas lawmakers proposed a New Communities Initiative pilot project to revitalize high-incarceration neighborhoods in Wichita that was not implemented because of budget cuts to the state’s corrections budget in the wake of the 2008 financial crisis. None of these early efforts resulted in or experienced sustained investments. International Justice Reinvestment Experiences The United Kingdom and Australia also took on justice reinvestment efforts. A detailed review of these is beyond the scope of this article and has been outlined elsewhere (e.g., Brown et al. 2016, Wong et al. 2014). In the United Kingdom, concerns about the growth in the size and costs of corrections led the House of Commons Justice Committee to question the financial sustainability of the system (Fox et al. 2013). Prison population growth was seen as the result of the justice system treating prison as a free commodity and not holding justice system actors accountable for the consequences of their decisions (Brown et al. 2016). As in the United States, the existence of high concentrations of offenders in certain areas sup- ported the idea that local solutions were necessary, and early thinking about justice reinvestment focused on how to enhance local control and provide support to communities. Local decision- makers were viewed as able to secure local support, coordinate resources, and work with offenders to integrate them into local programs that would also build capacity in local communities (Allen 2007, 2011). Local administration would also improve accountability and the administration of justice (Stern & Allen 2007, Wong et al. 2014). In practice, justice reinvestment as implemented in the United Kingdom has been described as narrow and focused on reducing individual reoffending and not on community reinvestment (Wong et al. 2014). It has been described as reflecting a choice by politicians to use the language of reinvestment to support a focus on reducing recidivism and costs, or “to make the ‘reinvestment’ a reality by capturing savings in the criminal justice system” (Brown et al. 2016, p. 61). A set of small-scale pilot projects were designed to divert offenders from custody or provide community- based, postrelease services for returning offenders. These were based on the delivery of a criminal justice services model rather than a community reinvestment model. However, the scale of the interventions was too small and the payments were insufficient to cover costs (Wong et al. 2014). In Australia, early interest in justice reinvestment among community groups and members of the federal government led to the commissioning of a Senate inquiry outlining the potential of jus- tice reinvestment to address the problem of overincarceration among the nation’s disadvantaged peoples (Brown et al. 2016). Despite widespread agreement that Aboriginal, Torres Strait Islander, and mentally or cognitively impaired peoples are disproportionately impacted by the Australian justice system and that a justice reinvestment program rooted in localism is well suited to address this disparity, plans for the development and implementation of a federally supported reform pro- gram have not come to fruition (Brown et al. 2016). Instead, the bulk of justice reinvestment in Australia has proceeded piecemeal in various communities through the efforts of local or regional grassroots organizations. Although these initiatives may be associated with concomitant reduc- tions in costs and increases in local social welfare indicators (KPMG 2018), few evaluations have been conducted. And, as evidence from the United Kingdom’s experience suggests, such small- scale programs may be limited in their capacity to produce substantial savings and change (Wong et al. 2014). 322 Sabol • Baumann A nn u. R ev . C ri m in ol . 2 02 0. 3: 31 7- 33 9. D ow nl oa de d fr om w w w .a nn ua lr ev ie w s. or g A cc es s pr ov id ed b y C ar ne gi e M el lo n U ni ve rs it y on 0 4/ 05 /2 1. F or p er so na l us e on ly . CR03CH15_Sabol ARjats.cls December 3, 2019 16:39 THE JUSTICE REINVESTMENT INITIATIVE JRI has been the dominant form of justice reinvestment practiced in the United States. It was distinct from justice reinvestment in several ways. First, its investment goal was justice system agencies and not community development. Second, although it promised that corrections costs would be saved by reducing imprisonment, its primary aim was to improve the efficiency of justice system operations and not large-scale reductions in incarceration. And third, it gave primacy to state-level agency stakeholders over community advocates. It was built on a model in which states secured support from key justice agency stakehold- ers; established bipartisan, interagency, or interbranch working groups of elected and appointed justice officials; used data to diagnose the sources of prison population growth; and enacted legis- lation or other evidence-based policy reforms to address the growth of correctional populations. JRI aimed to improve public safety while containing corrections costs (LaVigne et al. 2014). JRI’s public safety, cost-reduction, and cost-containment goals had broad bipartisan appeal. Cost con- tainment appealed to the political right. Reducing prison populations appealed to the political left. The emphasis on evidence-based practices appealed to those believing in the potential efficacy of government programs regardless of their political persuasion. JRI began in 2010 (LaVigne et al. 2014) with the first Congressional appropriation of $10 million for “activities related to comprehensive criminal justice reform and recidivism re- duction efforts by the States” (Pub. L. No. 111-117, 123 Stat. 3034, 2 U.S.C. § 661, p. 3,135). JRI was implemented as a public–private partnership between BJA and Pew, a rare if not unique orga- nizational arrangement within the Department of Justice. Between 2010 and 2017, Congress ap- propriated approximately $138 million for JRI (Harvell et al. 2017). In 2013 and 2016, BJA carved out JRI funds from other discretionary grant programs totaling approximately $33 million (OJP 2017). Prior to 2010, BJA also used funds from its discretionary grant programs to support JRI TA providers (OJP 2017). These sums suggest a BJA investment in JRI that exceeded $160 million. Justice Reinvestment Initiative Implementation JRI’s data-driven process (BJA 2010, 2013, 2015) involved seven steps (Davies et al. 2015, LaVigne et al. 2014, Welsh-Loveman & Harvell 2018) that fed back on themselves in a continuous cycle of reform: 1. Establish a bipartisan working group (inclusion criteria) 2. Analyze data and identify prison population drivers 3. Develop policy options 4. Codify and document changes 5. Implement policy changes 6. Reinvest savings 7. Measure outcomes BJA-funded TA providers worked with government officials to identify drivers of correctional population growth, evaluate the cost-effectiveness of state spending on corrections, and develop data-driven policy options to improve corrections management strategies, increase public safety, and improve offender accountability (BJA 2006, 2013). These Phase I activities included develop- ing bipartisan support for JRI efforts, building data infrastructures to track implementation and outcomes, demonstrating a willingness to implement evidence-based practices (EBPs) as part of JRI-reform efforts, and exhibiting the capacity to project what prison populations and corrections would be with and without the JRI reforms. Subsequently, states could become eligible for www.annualreviews.org • Justice Reinvestment 323 A nn u. R ev . C ri m in ol . 2 02 0. 3: 31 7- 33 9. D ow nl oa de d fr om w w w .a nn ua lr ev ie w s. or g A cc es s pr ov id ed b y C ar ne gi e M el lo n U ni ve rs it y on 0 4/ 05 /2 1. F or p er so na l us e on ly . CR03CH15_Sabol ARjats.cls December 3, 2019 16:39 Phase II grants for implementation. Phase II grant eligibility was based on a state’s readiness (i.e., having demonstrated a commitment to reform and the completion of Phase I activities), including memorializing criminal justice reforms in legislation or another mechanism and a willingness to implement JRI reforms (BJA 2013). TA providers assessed readiness and made recommendations to BJA regarding Phase II grants. BJA supported the work of an Oversight, Coordination, and Outcome Assessment (OCOA) to monitor, track, and report on JRI efforts, impacts, and outcomes. The OCOA was funded to accomplish multiple and potentially conflicting roles surrounding implementation and evaluation that included (BJA 2010, 2011, 2015): � Giving guidance to TA providers to ensure fidelity to the JRI model. � Reviewing TA provider recommendations about the readiness of states for JRI. � Making recommendations to BJA about relevant criminal justice research on ways to im- prove the effectiveness of JRI. � Providing guidance to BJA, TA providers, and the sites on performance measurement, data collection, and evaluation research. � Monitoring, tracking, and reporting on JRI efforts, impacts, and outcomes, including effects on prison population size, costs, investment in high-performing strategies, and improve- ments in public safety and reductions in recidivism. � Assessing which JRI strategies yielded the greatest impacts on public safety and producing a report on this. BJA funded the OCOA via a cooperative agreement mechanism that gave BJA a substantial role in the OCOA project, including the rights to review and approve OCOA activities.1 Justice Reinvestment Initiative’s Technical Assistance–Driven Model Led to a Shift in the Focus of Reinvestment JRI relied on TA providers to engage and enroll states, working with them to develop biparti- san stakeholder groups, engineer solutions that addressed prison population growth, and assess states’ readiness for JRI. The TA providers also made funding recommendations to BJA. The TA model resulted in a shift away from the focus on systemic and community factors tied to crimino- genic risk, as originally described by Tucker & Cadora (2003) and operationalized by Clear (2011). Rather, JRI’s reinvestment was put into state justice agencies, primarily community corrections, to improve their functioning. Whereas the community-reinvestment version of justice reinvestment was envisioned as a response to the problem of crime, JRI ultimately became a reform of criminal justice system processes practically designed to more effectively manage offenders. Brown et al. (2016, p. 115) note: As originally conceived in 2003, and as reimagined by Austin et al. in 2013, justice reinvestment has at its core not just decarceration, but community-driven local capacity building in the places most in need of positive change. In practice, however, we have seen that many of the cornerstone ideas of JR have been altered, reconceived or abandoned. The most significant of these shifts has been the move away from localized, place-based justice reinvestment, and the failure to reinvest savings in communities that produce large numbers of prisoners. Despite JRI’s broad, bipartisan political appeal, advocates of the original vision of community- based justice reinvestment argued that the system-level approach of JRI excluded the communities most affected by incarceration and did not address the problem of mass incarceration as originally 1The Urban Institute was selected as the OCOA through a competitive solicitation process. 324 Sabol • Baumann A nn u. R ev . C ri m in ol . 2 02 0. 3: 31 7- 33 9. D ow nl oa de d fr om w w w .a nn ua lr ev ie w s. or g A cc es s pr ov id ed b y C ar ne gi e M el lo n U ni ve rs it y on 0 4/ 05 /2 1. F or p er so na l us e on ly . CR03CH15_Sabol ARjats.cls December 3, 2019 16:39 envisioned (Austin et al. 2013). O’Hear (2017) argued that JRI’s focus on improving correctional efficiency was only tangentially related to the goal of reducing prison populations. These crit- icisms of JRI’s system-level approach concluded that the entities responsible for managing the large-scale correctional populations in the United States could not be counted on to reduce mass incarceration. Rather, as O’Hear suggested, JRI-empowered corrections officials would be more likely to use their enhanced capacities to respond to problems of chronic antisocial behavior with even more correctional control. These views coincide with those of other advocates of the original vision of justice reinvest- ment. For example, Vanita Gupta, eventually appointed as the Principal Deputy Assistant Attorney General to head the Civil Rights Division at the US Department of Justice, expressed similar con- cerns. She argued that by limiting the stakeholders primarily to state-level actors at the expense of local community stakeholders, JRI became a more conservative effort that limited the scope of reform so much that the JRI would not have an impact on mass incarceration (Brown et al. 2016). Ultimately, these advocates argued, this led JRI to become a conservative, status-quo-preserving reform effort (Austin et al. 2013). Ultimately, as we discuss later, JRI has not been shown to pro- duce reductions in prison populations. Hence, it is important to understand how JRI became a TA-driven and state-focused effort. We argue that two factors led to this. The first was federal funding priorities and the second was the expertise and experience of the entities that obtained funding through the competitive JRI grant programs. Dating back to and likely before the Government Performance Results Act of 1993 (Pub. L. 103-62, S.20), an evidence-based policy movement coincided with managerialism in the public sector and the belief that effective federal programs could be implemented indepen- dently of ideology and that federal performance could and should yield measurable benefits and results. By the mid-2000s, building on the work of Sherman and colleagues (Sherman et al. 2012) and the existence of “what works” clearinghouses, Laurie Robinson, the nominee for the Assistant Attorney General position for the Office of Justice Programs, described a role for federal funding to address crime that included developing and disseminating knowledge about what works and funding TA (COSSA 2010, Robinson 2017). Her testimony coincided with the evidence agenda promoted by the Office of Management and Budget (OMB). Beginning in the mid-2000s, OMB issued a series of memoranda to federal agencies in which it requested the agencies develop budget requests to strengthen the development and use of evidence, focus on a relatively small number of high-quality programs that would yield credible evidence of impacts, and direct larger shares of agency resources toward evidence-based practices (Burwell et al. 2013, Orszag 2009). As a federal programmatic, grant-making agency, BJA budget plans were subject to OMB review, and it had to align its objectives with OMB’s. Given the federal priority on evidence-based practices and the relative lack or absence of evidence about effective community-based justice reinvestment efforts coupled with knowledge of EBPs that focused on offenders’ risk and needs, federal funding priorities emphasized the evidence-based practices that helped to shift the focus of JRI toward the state-agency and TA-led models.2 Second,according to interviews conducted by Brown and colleagues,the focus on EBP was also associated with JRI’s move toward investments in criminal justice system improvements. This shift 2At CrimeSolutions.gov (https://crimesolutions.gov/TopicDetails.aspx?ID=35), the Justice Department’s “what works” clearinghouse for justice programs, there are no programs identified as evidence-based that mimic justice reinvestment into the community. By comparison, CrimeSolutions.gov identifies several reentry and community-corrections programs as evidence-based. These include intensive supervision, treatment for mentally ill inmates, reduced probation caseloads, and day treatment programs. www.annualreviews.org • Justice Reinvestment 325 A nn u. R ev . C ri m in ol . 2 02 0. 3: 31 7- 33 9. D ow nl oa de d fr om w w w .a nn ua lr ev ie w s. or g A cc es s pr ov id ed b y C ar ne gi e M el lo n U ni ve rs it y on 0 4/ 05 /2 1. F or p er so na l us e on ly . https://crimesolutions.gov/TopicDetails.aspx?ID=35) CR03CH15_Sabol ARjats.cls December 3, 2019 16:39 aligned with the expertise of the JRI TA providers that obtained the competitive grants that BJA provided for TA. Quoting TA providers, Brown et al. (2016) report that they believed that there was not a consensus regarding evidence-based methodologies for community development from justice-reinvested funds. By comparison, the criminogenic risk and needs literature (see James 2018 for a summary) provided guidance on EBPs. Furthermore, the EBP focus was consistent with JRI TA providers’ expertise in working with state agencies. The TA providers argued that a justice system focus for JRI better aligned with their skills and experience than a focus on com- munities (CSG 2013b). As Brown and colleagues report, one TA provider acknowledged “we’re not community redevelopment experts” (Brown et al. 2016, p. 95). Although JRI TA providers did not dispute the fact that disadvantaged communities had great needs, they also pointed to legitimate weaknesses in state corrections systems’ operations and argued that these problems needed to be addressed. These problems provided opportunities for change without needing to take a place-based approach to justice reinvestment. Thus, the combination of federal funding priorities, competitive grantmaking, and the experience and expertise of TA providers reinforced a state-agency model that reflected the expertise of the TA providers and addressed a reasonable need to improve agencies and the supervision that they provided. According to our argument, fed- eral funding priorities in combination with funded expertise combined to shift the focus of justice reinvestment toward corrections’ systems improvement. State Participation in the Justice Reinvestment Initiative Coincided with Widespread Legislative Sentencing Reforms Twenty-eight states participated in the JRI process between 2010 and 2016 (Harvell et al. 2017, LaVigne et al. 2014) and were included in the Urban Institute’s OCOA assessment reports.3 JRI states were defined as those involved in a time-limited JRI engagement that had previously en- gaged in criminal justice policymaking and intended to continue to do so after their JRI engage- ments end. This definition excluded California, which implemented justice reinvestment under Assembly Bill 109 following the US Supreme Court decision in Brown v. Plata (2011). That de- cision in 2011 ordered California to reduce the size of its prison population. AB 109 defined the purpose of justice reinvestment as “managing and allocating criminal justice populations more cost-effectively, generating savings that can be reinvested in evidence-based strategies that in- crease public safety while holding offenders accountable” (Petersilia 2014, p. 334). AB 109 aimed to support local community-based programs and EBPs. The Urban Institute’s reports on states’ JRI experiences describe what were identified as drivers of correctional population growth, the reform responses by the states, the adoption of EBPs, and estimates of impacts on prison populations and costs. Commonly reported prison popula- tion drivers among JRI states were parole and probation violations, with technical violations for drug and alcohol offenses identified as the primary cause of revocations in many states. Exist- ing sentencing practices and insufficient community corrections programs were also identified as drivers (Harvell et al. 2017, LaVigne et al. 2014). JRI practices varied among the states. Eighteen of the twenty-eight states that participated in JRI by 2016 adopted a variety of sentencing reforms, including changes to penalty classifications, mandatory and presumptive sentencing guidelines, sentencing enhancements, and alternative 3As Brown et al. (2016) and others point out, there were several, locally based justice reinvestment efforts, such as BJA’s funding for local jails (BJA 2008), and the Urban Institute produced a handbook for local practitioners on justice reinvestment (Parks et al. 2016). We exclude a discussion of these because they were few relative to the state JRI efforts and because of space limitations. 326 Sabol • Baumann A nn u. R ev . C ri m in ol . 2 02 0. 3: 31 7- 33 9. D ow nl oa de d fr om w w w .a nn ua lr ev ie w s. or g A cc es s pr ov id ed b y C ar ne gi e M el lo n U ni ve rs it y on 0 4/ 05 /2 1. F or p er so na l us e on ly . CR03CH15_Sabol ARjats.cls December 3, 2019 16:39 sentencing options. Twenty states implemented changes to their prison-release practices through practices such as expanded parole eligibility, use of good-time credits, and streamlined parole processes. Commonly enacted community corrections reforms included graduated sanctions, caps on the number of times a person can be revoked, and legislation to expand community-based supervision and treatment programs. JRI implementation occurred during a period of vigorous sentencing reform activity among the states. Between 2000 and 2016, every state in the United States passed legislation that had one or more elements of the types of legislative reforms that were documented as occurring under JRI. As cataloged in various state legislative tracking efforts by the National Conference of State Legislatures, the Sentencing Project, and the Vera Institute (Austin 2010; Brooke-Eisen & James 2012; Lawrence 2008; Mauer 2011; NCSL 2010, 2017; Porter 2017; Subramanian & Moreno 2014; Subramanian & Delany 2014), state legislative actions during this period addressed the use of EBPs and diversion programs and the possibility of requiring or encouraging the use of risk-assessment instruments, downgrading offenses (mostly property or drug), altering mandatory minimum sentences,expanding the use of specialty courts,adding alternatives to prison,increasing the use of good-time credits to shorten stays in prison, addressing parole revocation practices, and providing for programming to address returning prisoners. Although it is difficult to determine whether JRI caused the sentencing reform activity, the pace of legislative enactment appeared to increase during JRI. Our review of the dates that states enacted sentencing reforms indicates that the majority of the states that participated in JRI enacted JRI-type legislative reforms prior to their participation. One condition for JRI participation was evidence of sentencing and criminal justice reform, the passage of sentence legislation prior to participating in JRI could be viewed as evidence of a JRI impact on reform. The sentencing reforms of the 2000s,whether adopted before or during JRI,focused on making sentencing less severe, but according to the NRC and others, they did not substantially alter the major punitive laws passed during the 1980s and 1990s that increased certainty and severity of sentencing (Stemen & Rengifo 2011, 2012; Stoll & Raphael 2013; Tonry 2017; Travis et al. 2014). Rather, the NRC characterizes them as “relatively minor and target[ing] less serious offenses” (Travis et al. 2014, p. 74), even though the reforms rolled back some mandatory minimums (Luna 2017b). O’Hear (2017) echoes this conclusion and points out that reductions in sentencing for some offenses tended to be offset by increases for other offenses. JRI emphasized reserving prison space for persons who have committed serious or violent crimes or who pose a high public safety risk (BJA 2015, 2016). However, doing this means that large-scale reduction in prison populations could not occur, as more than half of state prisoners are incarcerated for violent crimes and most prisoners have long prior criminal histories. As a number of writers have pointed out, the key to reducing mass incarceration is reducing the number of persons held for violent offenses (Austin et al. 2013, Gottschalk 2015, O’Hear 2017, Pfaff 2017, Tonry 2017). Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS) data show that between 2000 and 2016, the increase in violent offenders accounted for almost all the growth in prison populations, with habitual and weapons offenders accounting for the next largest share. The number of state prison inmates held for violent crimes increased by 95,000 persons and the share held for violent offenses increased to 54% from approximately 50%. The exclusion of violent offenders from JRI efforts was nearly codified in federal law. In 2010, two bills were introduced in the 111th Congress (S.2772 and H.R. 4080) that would have estab- lished a JRI grant program. The top priority for JRI implementation grant recipients under the bills was to “improve public safety and improve individual and system accountability while reduc- ing or maintaining criminal justice growth through policies which ensure that—violent offenders are incarcerated…”) [S. 2772; Sec. 4(b)(6)(A)(i)]. www.annualreviews.org • Justice Reinvestment 327 A nn u. R ev . C ri m in ol . 2 02 0. 3: 31 7- 33 9. D ow nl oa de d fr om w w w .a nn ua lr ev ie w s. or g A cc es s pr ov id ed b y C ar ne gi e M el lo n U ni ve rs it y on 0 4/ 05 /2 1. F or p er so na l us e on ly . CR03CH15_Sabol ARjats.cls December 3, 2019 16:39 Neither bill made it to the floor for a vote, but the introduction of S.2772 was met with strong support from JRI TA providers, including CSG, Pew, and the Urban Institute. These TA providers provided testimonies on behalf of the bills.CSG,for example,applauded the bills (CSG 2013a) and devoted a page on its website to track the legislation. If the bills had been enacted, they would have precluded federal JRI efforts from addressing violent offenders. Despite the bills’ exclusions of violent offenders, CSG and the other providers supported the bipartisan nature of the legislation, the support for JRI grant programs, and the manner in which the legislation built on CSG’s efforts in other states. Other than considering that prison was appropriate for them, JRI did not address violent offenders. Adoption of Evidence-Based Practices Under the Justice Reinvestment Initiative Was Widespread but Left Unanswered Questions About Their Impacts A second area in which JRI had success was in the widespread adoption of risk-based tools to manage populations and the use of risk-and-needs tools to provide treatment. Twenty-one of the twenty-eight states that participated in JRI required the creation and/or use of risk instruments in the areas of pretrial diversion, community supervision, and parole decisions. These instruments are meant to inform justice officials’ decision-making by identifying low-risk offenders (i.e., non- violent) who are least likely to recidivate and would, therefore, be appropriate candidates for early release or community supervision. Ten states’ legislative reforms included explicit requirements that certain programs, especially in the areas of community corrections, be considered evidence- based to receive funding. At least 24 of the JRI states implemented EBP in community correc- tions (Harvell et al. 2017). These were based largely on the criminogenic risk and needs model (Lowenkamp et al. 2006). Although there was widespread adoption of EBP under JRI, concerns have been raised about this. Leading researchers in EBP point out that widespread but shallow adoption of EBP in com- munity corrections “recognizes the data points but has been missing the person” (Lowenkamp et al. 2012, p. 11). They argued that unless therapeutic practices were implemented correctly, cor- rectional officers could focus too much on compliance with supervision requirements and lose their ability to motivate behavior change (Lowenkamp et al. 2012) or that treatment based on in- strumental rather than humanistic values was not legitimate (Harris et al. 2015, Whitehead et al. 2007). Other EBP researchers echoed the concern about rapid adoption of EBP in community corrections agencies. Taxman (2013) argued that community corrections agencies operated for decades in a culture of command and control that emphasized contacts, a focus on proscribed behaviors, and threats of violations. To effectively use EBPs, the agencies would have to change their cultures and move away from an enforcement and contact-driven model to a more holistic approach to engaging offenders. Otherwise, as Klingele (2015, p. 540) pointed out, the risk of adopting EBPs without the culture change and with “conscious attention to their limits” is that they can result in greater use of incarceration in response to proscribed behaviors. A second concern was that by measuring the adoption of EBPs as an indicator of success, JRI was measuring the wrong thing. Rather than counting and classifying various EBPs adopted in JRI states as the summary reports did (e.g., Harvell et al. 2017, LaVigne et al. 2013), Taxman and colleagues (Taxman et al.2014) argued that JRI performance measures for EBP should focus on the measures of offender needs, system-wide availability of EBPs that were responsive to these needs, and system-wide utilization of the EBPs. Taxman’s measures make sense if the goal is to assess the capacity of states to meet offender needs and to deliver services. These alternative performance measures have not been included in the state assessment reports. 328 Sabol • Baumann A nn u. R ev . C ri m in ol . 2 02 0. 3: 31 7- 33 9. D ow nl oa de d fr om w w w .a nn ua lr ev ie w s. or g A cc es s pr ov id ed b y C ar ne gi e M el lo n U ni ve rs it y on 0 4/ 05 /2 1. F or p er so na l us e on ly . CR03CH15_Sabol ARjats.cls December 3, 2019 16:39 The Justice Reinvestment Initiative Overstated the Potential Savings A major motivation for participating in JRI was its promise of lower-cost corrections systems. Clear (2011) and Pfaff (2016) describe this as using the fiscal crisis following the Great Recession as an opportunity for reform. The argument for lower-cost corrections was based on the 40-year low in crime rates coupled with all-time highs in prison populations and corrections spending. JRI advocates argued that prison populations could be safely reduced, thereby freeing up some of the corrections expenditures for other purposes, including funding community corrections. As described in one of the state assessment reports, state corrections expenditures consumed too large a proportion of states’ budgets, and during periods of state budget strain, “money spent on corrections draws resources away from investment in public services crucial to a state’s long-term prosperity, such as education and infrastructure” (LaVigne et al. 2014, p. 6). This popular argument about corrections expenditures appears in different forms, including the NRC report (Travis et al. 2014) and reports by the Vera Institute and the National Association of State Budget Officers (NASBO). These reports cite the increase in corrections expenditures over time and report a roughly $80 billion figure (in 2016) spent by states and counties on prisons and jails as indications that corrections expenditures are too high. All of these reports share a focus on the absolute amount of corrections spending but not the relatively small share of total state and local expenditures that is corrections spending. In relative terms, corrections expenditures amount to approximately 2% of all state and lo- cal expenditures (roughly $3.6 trillion in 2016). Gottschalk (2015), along with BJS (Kyckelhahn 2012), is among the few who pointed out that state and county corrections expenditures amount to small shares of total expenditures. Consequently, they cannot be a major source of strain on budgets and reducing them would not necessarily solve states’ budget problems. Our analysis of the Annual Survey of State Government Finance (US Census Bur. 2019) shows, for example, that although state spending on corrections increased over time,corrections spending as a share of total state expenditures did not exceed 3.2% annually from 1980 to 2015. State spending on corrections increased with the overall increase in state expenditures.Between 2000 and 2016,total state expen- ditures increased from $1.1 trillion to $2.2 trillion (in nominal dollars), but during these years, the corrections spending as a share of total state spending actually declined from 3% to 2.4%.4 Fur- thermore, Spelman (2009) points out that corrections spending grew at approximately the same rate as state expenditures for education, health and hospitals, highways, and other categories. Data from the NASBO corroborate the US Census Bureau data on corrections expenditures. NASBO’s reports also show that corrections expenditures declined as a share of total state ex- penditures, for example, from 3.7% of total state expenditures in 2000 to 3.1% in 2016 (NASBO 2002, 2017).5 Reductions in state corrections expenditures promised under JRI could not ease state budget pressures or markedly affect the share of state expenditures that went to other domains, as alleged. For example, between 2000 and 2015, education expenditures declined as a share of total state ex- penditures from 32% to 29%. During the same period, public welfare expenditures grew faster 4Results available from the authors upon request. 5In its state assessment report, the Urban Institute reports a larger share of state expenditures going to cor- rections than reported above. The reason is that Urban uses general fund expenditures as the denominator to calculate the share, whereas we and NASBO use total expenditures. Because corrections expenditures come from four sources—general fund, bonds, other state funds, and federal funds—excluding, as the Urban Insti- tute did, nongeneral fund expenditures from its denominator but including them in the numerator to calculate the corrections expenditures inflates that share (see NASBO 2002, 2017). www.annualreviews.org • Justice Reinvestment 329 A nn u. R ev . C ri m in ol . 2 02 0. 3: 31 7- 33 9. D ow nl oa de d fr om w w w .a nn ua lr ev ie w s. or g A cc es s pr ov id ed b y C ar ne gi e M el lo n U ni ve rs it y on 0 4/ 05 /2 1. F or p er so na l us e on ly . CR03CH15_Sabol ARjats.cls December 3, 2019 16:39 than the overall growth in state expenditures,and their share increased from 22% to approximately 29% (or from approximately $239 billion to $609 billion). If the entirety of state corrections ex- penditures were reallocated to state education expenditures, the education share would still have declined over this time frame, from 35% to 31%. In fact, increases in public welfare expendi- tures, and not corrections expenditures, exerted the downward pressure on state investments in education. JRI advocates also missed or ignored four other important points about corrections expendi- tures. First, the estimates of cost savings under JRI were generally overstated because they were based on the average cost of an inmate and not the marginal cost (Tonry 2011, Gottschalk 2015). As approximately 75% of corrections spending goes to fixed costs (e.g., salaries, debt service) that do not change with small reductions in the size of prison populations, the marginal cost of an additional prison is approximately one-fifth the average costs (Pfaff 2016). Second, significant reductions in prison population size that led to prison closures would present challenges to states dealing with subsequent reductions in their workforce (Tonry 2011). These were not addressed in JRI strategies. Gottschalk (2015) points out that if reforms are justi- fied by reference to cost savings, the reforms will generate the savings only if they cut the size of correctional staff. Corrections budgets in many states are protected by public-sector unions, and reductions in force associated with much smaller prison populations would face opposition, if not from public-sector unions then from public-sector lobbying groups. But third, as Gottschalk (2015) also points out, it is not obvious that decarceration that does not lead to increases in crime is necessarily less expensive than prison. Rehabilitation programs that address offender needs related to substance abuse, mental health, housing, employment, and education are not cheap, especially if well-run. Finally, fiscal-based reforms such as JRI run the risk of leading to worse conditions in prisons. If state prison departments are under pressure to save money or to transfer it to other agencies before significant reductions in prison populations have occurred, this could lead to worse conditions for prison inmates. In sum, the pressure on state budgets arising from corrections expenditures was overstated and the efforts necessary to achieve significant reductions in corrections expenditures could lead to new problems for states. These were not presented as part of the case for JRI. The Justice Reinvestment Initiative Resulted in Several States Making Up-Front Investments According to the state assessment reports, JRI was associated with projected savings or averted costs, which were estimated as the difference between the projected future costs of corrections under business as usual and the projected costs under JRI. The difference is averted costs. Among the seventeen JRI states that participated between 2010 and 2013, total projected savings from JRI were reportedly $4.6 billion over five to eleven years. Individual state estimates of savings ranged from $7.7 to $875 million (LaVigne et al. 2014). For the 28 states that participated in JRI between 2010 and 2016, a total of $1.1 billion in savings or costs averted were attributed to JRI reforms (Harvell et al. 2017). The differences in estimated savings arise from initial comparisons of projected savings as compared to later comparisons with some actual changes under JRI. Reinvestment strategies varied considerably across states. According to Harvell et al. (2017), four states made up-front investments via new legislative appropriations before the realization of actual savings, another 12 states implemented both up-front investment and postreform rein- vestment strategies, and four states reinvested real savings. Only four states did neither. In to- tal, $193 million in up-front investments and $364 million in corrections savings reinvestments were made among JRI states that participated in reinvestment strategies (Welsh-Loveman & 330 Sabol • Baumann A nn u. R ev . C ri m in ol . 2 02 0. 3: 31 7- 33 9. D ow nl oa de d fr om w w w .a nn ua lr ev ie w s. or g A cc es s pr ov id ed b y C ar ne gi e M el lo n U ni ve rs it y on 0 4/ 05 /2 1. F or p er so na l us e on ly . CR03CH15_Sabol ARjats.cls December 3, 2019 16:39 Harvell 2018). Most states’ investments focused on expanding community-based treatment pro- grams, postrelease services, and community supervision. A few states injected JRI-related funds into prison programs, victim services, diversion courts, law enforcement agencies, and pretrial diversion programs. None of the JRI states made investments in community revitalization or pri- mary prevention programs in high-incarceration neighborhoods or outside of the justice system. The fact that at least four states appropriated new monies for JRI through the up-front invest- ment mechanism suggests that under some circumstances, state legislatures can be persuaded to appropriate current dollars based on expectations of future cost savings. The fact that only a few states used the future cost savings argument to support requests for new expenditures suggests that the future cost savings argument did not have a strong appeal to state legislatures. However, the fact that it appealed to some state legislatures raises important questions about how and why it worked in some but not others. A study that considers whether there are lessons to be learned for state budgeting is merited. The Justice Reinvestment Initiative Did Not Demonstrate That It Contributed to Reductions in Prison Populations The JRI state assessment reports claimed that for 15 of the 18 states that participated in JRI by 2016 and for whom “sufficient time had passed to warrant analysis,” the prison population in 2015 was below what was projected without JRI reforms (Harvell et al. 2017, p. viii). Sufficient time was defined as at least two years of follow-up data since JRI legislative reforms were enacted (Harvell et al. 2017). This assessment was based on comparisons of the projected prison population under JRI reforms to the baseline projected populations that would have occurred had reforms not been implemented. This method allows the prison population to increase under JRI and be counted as a success as long as JRI-projected increases were less than baseline projected increases. The use of baseline forecasts of future prison populations conducted before a reform is imple- mented to generate the counterfactual future prison populations that would be obtained without the reforms has merit under certain conditions. The baseline forecasts should be accurate and have low error, and the length of the forecast period over which the comparisons are made should be reasonable. Assumptions about admissions and length of stay, the two determinants of the size of the prison population (Clear & Austin 2017), need to be assessed, along with the accuracy of the forecast models and the forecast error, particularly over the longer run. Of concern is the extent to which the population forecasts adequately assessed these factors. We could not find in the JRI state assessment reports (Harvell et al. 2017) any information indicating that such a critical review of the forecast models was done. We found no evidence that the reviews assessed assumptions, accuracy, or forecast error over the short or long run. Austin et al. (2013) raised questions about the accuracy of the JRI baseline forecast models. They argued that, in anticipation of participating in JRI, state forecast models used assumptions about admissions growth that were higher than during the period immediately prior to their JRI engagement. This would translate into larger baseline projections of prison populations that would, in turn, put less demand on JRI reforms to affect forecast and actual populations. Austin & Coventry (2014) provide examples of how baseline forecasts in some JRI states did not use all available information; if they had used them, smaller populations would have been forecast and reported JRI impacts may have vanished. The aforementioned absence of information about assessments of the reliability of prison population forecasts leads us to discount the JRI state as- sessment reports of reductions in prison populations. Comparisons of differences in prison population growth between JRI and non-JRI states have found negligible reductions in both but larger decreases in non-JRI states. Austin et al. (2013) and www.annualreviews.org • Justice Reinvestment 331 A nn u. R ev . C ri m in ol . 2 02 0. 3: 31 7- 33 9. D ow nl oa de d fr om w w w .a nn ua lr ev ie w s. or g A cc es s pr ov id ed b y C ar ne gi e M el lo n U ni ve rs it y on 0 4/ 05 /2 1. F or p er so na l us e on ly . CR03CH15_Sabol ARjats.cls December 3, 2019 16:39 Austin & Coventry (2014) looked at the early years of JRI and compared JRI and non-JRI states on prison population, admissions, and length of stay. The largest decreases in prison populations occurred in four non-JRI states (NY, NJ, MI, and CA). Reductions in admissions due to decreases in parole violators were larger in the non-JRI states, as were the very small changes in length of stay in either group.6 A criticism levied against the Austin work is that the selection into JRI was based in part on the assumption of a projected high rate of growth in prison population. In other words, the JRI states would start from a higher base and therefore reductions might be smaller. This claim is questionable. Prison population growth in the United States slowed in the early 2000s (Harrison & Beck 2003, 2004, 2005), and by the mid-2000s when JRI was implemented, prison population growth nationwide was approaching zero growth. Although rates of growth varied among the states, those selected into JRI in 2007 and 2008 (KS, NV, TX, AZ, CT, PA, RI) included a mixture of states with smaller and larger than average growth in prison populations as reported by the BJS (Sabol et al. 2007). The same conclusion applies to the states selected into JRI in 2010 and 2011 (MI, NH, SC, AL, AR, KY, LA, NC, OH) except that several of these JRI states reported decreases in their prison populations in the year or years prior to entry into JRI (West et al. 2010). Overall, in 18 of the 35 states that participated in JRI, declines in prison populations began before their year of entry into JRI. An alternative approach to identifying causal effects of JRI on prison populations was suggested by Rhodes and colleagues (W. Rhodes, G. Gaes, T. Rich, J. Edgerton, R. Kling, J. Luallen, unpub- lished report). Using administrative data on persons admitted into and released from state prisons, they adopted a difference-in-difference (DiD) framework to compare pre- and post-JRI popula- tion trends in the targeted and comparison populations within JRI states. They defined target and comparison groups based on the severity of sentence served, under the theory that effective sentence length incorporates decision makers’ assessments of offender severity and risk (Bushway & Smith 2007; Kuziemko 2007, 2014). The insight behind this approach is that if JRI diverted less serious or lower-risk offenders from prison as expected, their admissions rates would decline following JRI and decline more rapidly than those of their comparison group, the next highest risk category. Their preliminary results for five JRI states found JRI-led reductions in some states but not in others (W. Rhodes, G. Gaes, T. Rich, J. Edgerton, R. Kling, J. Luallen, unpublished report). The Rhodes’ example illustrates an approach not taken to assess impacts of JRI on prison populations. It addresses some of the concerns about selection into JRI by making comparisons within JRI states before and after implementation. It identifies a group (lower level offenders) that should be impacted by JRI reforms and compares changes for that group of offenders with groups that should not be affected by reforms to identify JRI impacts, such as more serious offenders. Finally, it presents a stronger design than the comparisons of actual to projected populations used in the state assessment reports. The Justice Reinvestment Initiative’s Evidence on Public Safety Impact We could find no peer-reviewed publications on the impacts of JRI on public safety. Several TA provider descriptive reports present information supporting the claim that “many JRI states have slowed prison growth, reduced overcrowding, and saved taxpayers’ money without sacrificing 6We updated the Austin et al. comparison between JRI and non-JRI states on prison population growth, extending the period covered through 2016. Our findings were similar to Austin’s: Both groups experienced relatively small decreases: California accounted for most of the decrease in non-JRI states, but when California was omitted the non-JRI states still had faster decreases, and several JRI states experienced decreases before participating in JRI. Analyses available upon request of the authors. 332 Sabol • Baumann A nn u. R ev . C ri m in ol . 2 02 0. 3: 31 7- 33 9. D ow nl oa de d fr om w w w .a nn ua lr ev ie w s. or g A cc es s pr ov id ed b y C ar ne gi e M el lo n U ni ve rs it y on 0 4/ 05 /2 1. F or p er so na l us e on ly . CR03CH15_Sabol ARjats.cls December 3, 2019 16:39 public safety and other states are projected to do so” (LaVigne 2014, p. 2). A core promise of JRI was that states could have smaller prison populations and improved public safety, or at least no decreases in public safety. According to BJA award documentation, one of the OCOA responsi- bilities was to measure the impacts of the JRI-led policy changes and “assess which JRI strategies yielded the greatest impact on public safety” (BJA 2011, p. 1). In the final state assessment re- port that was available at the time of this writing, public safety outcomes—specifically crime and recidivism rates—were defined as core system-level measures, but the report omitted any presen- tation of data on these measures (Harvell et al. 2017). The omission of any information about JRI’s impacts on public safety precludes any assessment of its benefits relative to costs. Admittedly, identifying JRI’s effects on public safety presents challenges. Given the varied na- ture of JRI implementation, the many reforms implemented at different times in different ways and the absence of detailed information about the EBPs, designs to measure impacts might require linked data on individuals that measure the interventions they receive and assess their outcomes. Furthermore, there may be a lag between the implementation of JRI and its impacts. However, several states had implemented JRI efforts as early as 2010. By the time of the most recent state assessment report in 2017, there were five to six years to observe impacts in early JRI adopters. This provides a sufficient length of time to conduct at least some preliminary analysis of JRI’s impacts on public safety. Furthermore, there are examples of models that could have been used to attempt to identify the impacts of JRI on public safety. The Bartos & Kurbin (2018) state-level panel with a synthetic control group design to estimate crime rates in the absence of a reform is one such model. Given the variety of approaches taken by states, it seems likely that state-specific assessments would be necessary. Because of the centrality of public safety to JRI, the absence of a public record of work done on this issue and the absence of evidence about JRI’s impacts on public safety are disappointing gaps in knowledge about what JRI may have accomplished and whether the federal investment paid off. CONCLUSIONS As practiced in the United States, justice reinvestment as originally conceived and the JRI have not achieved their goals. The original version of justice reinvestment did not achieve its objective of redirecting a portion of corrections expenditures toward community needs or in devolving accountability for offenders from the state to the local communities in which offenders resided. The JRI, which had success in enrolling states, accelerating the pace of legislative change, and adopting EBPs, did not demonstrate that it led to reductions in prison populations, cost savings, or improvements in public safety. An appeal of the community-oriented approach of the original justice reinvestment was its aim to rearrange the relationship between communities and corrections systems, as reflected by its em- phasis on devolving accountability for offenders to their local communities. At that level, it passes Western’s test for using criminal justice policy to address social problems by encouraging commu- nity membership and participation (Western 2018). But the community-oriented approach of the original justice reinvestment does not address funding and implementation challenges. It did not demonstrate that even relatively large reductions in prison populations would generate sufficient savings to address the reinvestment needs; that local communities had sufficient infrastructure to sustain alternatives to incarceration; that states would be willing to devolve authority to the very localities that they blamed for sending them so many prisoners in the first place; that state legisla- tures would use savings for local community reinvestment as opposed to other state-level budget needs; or that state legislatures would commit to appropriating funds to cover a future stream of www.annualreviews.org • Justice Reinvestment 333 A nn u. R ev . C ri m in ol . 2 02 0. 3: 31 7- 33 9. D ow nl oa de d fr om w w w .a nn ua lr ev ie w s. or g A cc es s pr ov id ed b y C ar ne gi e M el lo n U ni ve rs it y on 0 4/ 05 /2 1. F or p er so na l us e on ly . CR03CH15_Sabol ARjats.cls December 3, 2019 16:39 projected savings, i.e., the future funds that would sustain community reinvestment, derived from the offenders diverted from prison. Even if local communities successfully supervised diverted of- fenders, the benefit of this would accrue to state prisons, which in turn would have to convince state legislatures to appropriate funds to cover the costs of prison populations that would have been obtained without the local justice reinvestment rather than their actual populations. Other- wise, the state support for justice reinvestment would not be sustained. Ultimately, the funding for community reinvestment needs to come from non-justice system sources. Practically, attempts to try justice reinvestment were short-lived, so we do not know if a model could have been designed to meet the funding and implementation challenges, although we doubt it.The JRI model supplanted the community-oriented justice reinvestment model and become the dominant form of justice reinvestment practiced in the United States. The JRI was implemented at a time when the federal government emphasized creating, dis- seminating, and using evidence to support its programs. Other than supporting the use of EBPs, JRI’s implementation did not align with the federal government’s evidence agenda. Rather than, say, fund a relatively small number of high-quality and proven programs (an OMB preference), JRI enrolled 28 states that implemented approximately as many untested and unproven vari- eties of reform. Or, rather than first demonstrate the efficacy of a few models and then funding them for broader implementation, JRI optioned for broad implementation of reforms without ev- idence that they would work. JRI’s elevation of enrollment over creating evidence leaves us with scant evidence of its effectiveness in achieving its goals, and no evidence that it improved public safety. JRI was associated with the adoption of sentencing reforms and with an acceleration of the pace of change, even if the reforms did not address the severity of the sentencing reforms of the 1990s. JRI helped to spread EBPs, especially in community supervision. The upside to the adoption of these reforms is that they have the potential to change the nature of community supervision. At the same time, the downside is that they have the potential to be implemented instrumentally and not in a humanistic manner, as their creators envisioned, unless the culture of community supervision agencies changes. At the time of this writing, federal support for JRI appears to be waning. BJA zeroed out JRI in its FY2019 budget and again in its FY2020 budget (OJP 2018, 2019). This suggests that federal support to assist agencies in the culture change necessary for safe, humane, and effective implementation of the EBP is likely dissipating. JRI’s bipartisan approach to reform also found room for political compromises that were crafted around improving the operation of justice agencies. By design, JRI could not achieve substantial reductions in prison populations or significant cost savings because it did not deal with violent offenders or those with long criminal histories (other than reserve prison space for them). These offenders make up the vast majority of prisoners. Achieving substantial reductions in the number of violent offenders in prison would have required JRI to address (reduce) the severity of sentencing and (increase) the use of alternatives to prison. These are not issues around which bipartisan compromise could have been easily forged within the confines of the program. Rather, JRI set a relatively low bar for reducing prison populations, oversold the potential cost savings, and ultimately did not deliver evidence that it was responsible for either. DISCLOSURE STATEMENT The authors are not aware of any affiliations, memberships, funding, or financial holdings that might be perceived as affecting the objectivity of this review. 334 Sabol • Baumann A nn u. R ev . C ri m in ol . 2 02 0. 3: 31 7- 33 9. D ow nl oa de d fr om w w w .a nn ua lr ev ie w s. or g A cc es s pr ov id ed b y C ar ne gi e M el lo n U ni ve rs it y on 0 4/ 05 /2 1. F or p er so na l us e on ly . CR03CH15_Sabol ARjats.cls December 3, 2019 16:39 LITERATURE CITED Allen R. 2007. From restorative prisons to justice reinvestment. See Allen & Stern 2007, pp. 5–8 Allen R. 2011. Justice reinvestment and the use of imprisonment. Criminol. Public Policy 10:617–27 Allen R, Stern V, eds. 2007.Justice Reinvestment–A New Approach to Crime and Justice. London: Int. Cent. Prison Stud. Austin A. 2010. Criminal justice trends: key legislative changes in sentencing policy, 2001–2010. Rep., Vera Inst. Justice, New York. https://storage.googleapis.com/vera-web-assets/downloads/Publications/ criminal-justice-trends-key-legislative-changes-in-sentencing-policy-2001-2010/legacy_ downloads/Sentencing-policy-trends-v1alt-v4.pdf Austin J. 2011. Making imprisonment unprofitable. Criminol. Public Policy 10:629–35 Austin J, Cadora E, Clear TR, Dansky K, Greene J, et al. 2013. Ending mass incarceration: charting a new justice reinvestment. Rep., Sentencing Proj., Washington, DC. https://www.sentencingproject.org/wp- content/uploads/2015/12/Ending-Mass-Incarceration-Charting-a-New-Justice-Reinvestment. pdf Austin J, Coventry G. 2014. A critical analysis of justice reinvestment in the United States and Australia. Vict. Offenders 9:126–48 Bartos BJ, Kubrin CE. 2018. Can we downsize our prisons and jails without compromising public safety? Findings from California’s Prop 47. Criminol. Public Policy 17:1–23 Bronson J, Carson AE. 2019. Prisoners in 2017. Bur. Justice Stat. Rep. NCJ 252156, US Dep. Justice, Washington, DC Brooke-Eisen L, James J. 2012. Reallocating justice resources: a review of 2011 state sentencing trends. Rep., Vera Inst. Justice, New York. https://storage.googleapis.com/vera-web-assets/downloads/Publications/ reallocating-justice-resources-a-review-of-2011-state-sentencing-trends/legacy_downloads/ reallocating-justice-resources.pdf Brown D, Cunneen C, Schwartz M, Stubbs J, Young C. 2016. Justice Reinvestment: Winding Back Imprisonment, Palgrave Studies in Prisons and Penology. Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave Macmillan Brown v. Plata, 563 U.S. 493 (2011) Bur. Justice Assist. (BJA). 2006. BJA’s prison population analyses: providing policymakers with data-driven anal- yses and options. Office Justice Program Grant 2006-RP-BX-K276, US Dep. Justice, Washington, DC. https://external.ojp.usdoj.gov/selector/awardDetail?awardNumber=2006-RP-BX-K276& fiscalYear=2006&applicationNumber=2006-F4814-KY-DD&programOffice=BJA&po=All Bur. Justice Assist. (BJA). 2008.Reducing jail populations, improving communities: a strategic approach for justice rein- vestmentat the local level.Office Justice Program Grant 2008-DD-BX-0684,US Dep.Justice,Washington, DC. https://external.ojp.usdoj.gov/selector/awardDetail?awardNumber=2008-DD-BX-0684& fiscalYear=2008&applicationNumber=2008-F5022-DC-MI&programOffice=BJA&po=BJA Bur. Justice Assist. (BJA). 2010. Criminal justice improvement and recidivism reduction through state, local, and tribal justice reinvestment: FY 2010 competitive grant announcement. Office Manag. Budg. Rep. 1121–0329, US Dep. Justice, Washington, DC. https://www.ncjrs.gov/pdffiles1/nij/sl001084.pdf Bur. Justice Assist. (BJA). 2011. Justice reinvestment initiative. Office Justice Program Grant 2010- RR-BX-K072, US Dep. Justice, Washington, DC. https://external.ojp.usdoj.gov/selector/ awardDetail?awardNumber=2010-RR-BX-K072&fiscalYear=2011&applicationNumber=2011- H6539-DC-TR&programOffice=BJA&po=BJA Bur. Justice Assist. (BJA). 2013. Criminal justice improvement and recidivism reduction through the state-level justice reinvestment initiative (JRI): FY 2013 competitive grant announcement. Office Manag. Budg. Rep. 1121– 0329, US. Dep. Justice, Washington, DC. https://www.bja.gov/Funding/13JRIsol.pdf Bur. Justice Assist. (BJA). 2015. Justice reinvestment initiative: maximizaing state reforms: FY 2015 competitive grant announcement. Office Manag. Budg. Rep. 112-0329, US. Dep. Justice, Washington, DC Bur. Justice Assist. (BJA). 2016. Justice reinvestment initiative: maximizing state reforms: FY 2016 competitive grant announcement. Office Manag. Budg. Rep. No. 1121–0329, US. Dep. Justice, Washington, DC. https:// www.bja.gov/funding/JRImaximizing.pdf www.annualreviews.org • Justice Reinvestment 335 A nn u. R ev . C ri m in ol . 2 02 0. 3: 31 7- 33 9. D ow nl oa de d fr om w w w .a nn ua lr ev ie w s. or g A cc es s pr ov id ed b y C ar ne gi e M el lo n U ni ve rs it y on 0 4/ 05 /2 1. F or p er so na l us e on ly . https://storage.googleapis.com/vera-web-assets/downloads/Publications/criminal-justice-trends-key-legislative-changes-in-sentencing-policy-2001-2010/legacy_downloads/Sentencing-policy-trends-v1alt-v4.pdf https://www.sentencingproject.org/wp-content/uploads/2015/12/Ending-Mass-Incarceration-Charting-a-New-Justice-Reinvestment.pdf https://storage.googleapis.com/vera-web-assets/downloads/Publications/reallocating-justice-resources-a-review-of-2011-state-sentencing-trends/legacy_downloads/reallocating-justice-resources.pdf https://external.ojp.usdoj.gov/selector/awardDetail?awardNumber = 2006-RP-BX-K276&fiscalYear = 2006&applicationNumber = 2006-F4814-KY-DD&programOffice = BJA&po = All https://external.ojp.usdoj.gov/selector/awardDetail?awardNumber = 2008-DD-BX-0684&fiscalYear = 2008&applicationNumber = 2008-F5022-DC-MI&programOffice = BJA&po = BJA https://www.ncjrs.gov/pdffiles1/nij/sl001084.pdf https://external.ojp.usdoj.gov/selector/awardDetail?awardNumber = 2010-RR-BX-K072&fiscalYear = 2011&applicationNumber = 2011-H6539-DC-TR&programOffice = BJA&po = BJA https://www.bja.gov/Funding/13JRIsol.pdf https://www.bja.gov/funding/JRImaximizing.pdf CR03CH15_Sabol ARjats.cls December 3, 2019 16:39 Burwell SM. 2013. Memorandum to the heads of departments and agencies. Office Manag. Budg. Rep. M-13-17, US. Dep. Justice, Washington, DC Bushway S, Smith J. 2007. Sentencing using statistical treatment rules: what we don’t know can hurt us. J. Quantit. Criminol. 23:377–87 Carson EA. 2018. Prisoners in 2016. Bur. Justice Stat. Rep. NCJ 241149, US Dep. Justice, Washington, DC Clear TR. 2008. The effects of high imprisonment rates on communities. Crime Justice 37:97–132 Clear TR. 2011. A private-sector, incentives-based model for justice reinvestment. Criminology Public Policy 10:585–608 Clear TR, Austin J. 2017. Mass incarceration. In Reforming Criminal Justice: Punishment, Incarceration, and Release, Vol. 4, ed. E Luna, pp. 55–76. Phoenix: Ariz. State Univ. Clear TR, Rose DR, Waring E, Scully K. 2003. Coercive mobility and crime: a preliminary examination of concentrated incarceration and social disorganization. Justice Q. 20:33–64 Clement M, Schwarzfeld M, Thompson M. 2011. The national summit on justice reinvestment and public safety: addressing recidivism, crime, and corrections spending. Justice Cent. Rep., Counc. State Gov., Washington, DC. https://csgjusticecenter.org/jr/summit-report/ COSSA. 2010. AAG Robinson defends OJP budget to House Appropriations panel. Wash. Update 29:4–5 Counc. State Gov. (CSG). 2003. Building bridges: from conviction to employment. Justice Cent. Rep., Counc. State Gov., Washington, DC. https://csgjusticecenter.org/wp-content/uploads/2012/12/Building. Bridges.pdf Counc. State Gov. (CSG). 2013a. CSG Justice Center applauds U.S. House and Senate members’ in- troduction of the Justice and Mental Health Collaboration Act. CSG Justice Center News. https:// csgjusticecenter.org/cp/press-releases/csg-justice-center-applauds-u-s-house-and-senate- members-introduction-of-the-justice-and-mental-health-collaboration-act/ Counc. State Gov. (CSG). 2013b. Lessons from the states: reducing recidivism and curbing corrections costs through justice reinvestment. Justice Cent. Rep., Counc. State Gov., Washington, DC. https://csgjusticecenter. org/wp-content/uploads/2013/04/FINAL_State_Lessons_mbedit.pdf Davies E,Harvell S,Cramer L.2015.TheJusticeReinvestmentInitiative: thinking local for state justicereinvestment. Rep. 2000158, Urban Inst., Washington, DC Fox C, Albertson K, Wong K. 2013. Justice Reinvestment: Can the Criminal Justice System Deliver More for Less? London: Routledge Gottschalk M. 2015. Caught: The Prison State and the Lockdown of American Politics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univ. Press Harris GT, Lowenkamp CT, Hilton NZ. 2015. Evidence for risk estimate precision: implications for individ- ual risk communication. Behav. Sci. Law 33:111–27 Harrison PM, Beck AJ. 2003. Prisoners in 2002. Bur. Justice Stat. Rep. NCJ 200248, Office Justice Progr., Washington, DC Harrison PM, Beck AJ. 2004. Prisoners in 2003. Bur. Justice Stat. Rep. NCJ 205335, Office Justice Progr., Washington, DC Harrison PM, Beck AJ. 2005. Prisoners in 2004. Bur. Justice Stat. Rep. NCJ 210677, Office Justice Progr., Washington, DC Harvell S, Welsh-Loveman J, Love H, Durnan J, Eisenstat J, et al. 2017. Reforming sentencing and corrections policy: the experience of justice reinvestment initiative states. Rep., Urban Inst. Washington, DC. https:// www.urban.org/sites/default/files/publication/86691/reforming_sentencing_and_corrections_ policy_final.pdf James N. 2018. Risk and needs assessment in the federal prison system. Rep. R44087, Congressional Res. Serv., Washington, DC Kleiman MAR. 2011. Justice reinvestment in community supervision. Criminol. Public Policy 10:651–59 Klingele C. 2015. The promises and perils of evidence-based corrections. Notre Dame Law Rev. 91:537–84 KPMG. 2018. Maranguka justice reinvestment project: impact assessment. Rep., Just Reinvest NSW, Sydney, Aust. http://www.justreinvest.org.au/wp-content/uploads/2018/11/Maranguka-Justice- Reinvestment-Project-KPMG-Impact-Assessment-FINAL-REPORT.pdf Kurgan L. 2013. Close Up at a Distance: Mapping, Technology, and Politics. New York: Zone Books 336 Sabol • Baumann A nn u. R ev . C ri m in ol . 2 02 0. 3: 31 7- 33 9. D ow nl oa de d fr om w w w .a nn ua lr ev ie w s. or g A cc es s pr ov id ed b y C ar ne gi e M el lo n U ni ve rs it y on 0 4/ 05 /2 1. F or p er so na l us e on ly . https://csgjusticecenter.org/jr/summit-report/ https://csgjusticecenter.org/wp-content/uploads/2012/12/Building.Bridges.pdf https://csgjusticecenter.org/cp/press-releases/csg-justice-center-applauds-u-s-house-and-senate-members-introduction-of-the-justice-and-mental-health-collaboration-act/ https://csgjusticecenter.org/wp-content/uploads/2013/04/FINAL_State_Lessons_mbedit.pdf https://www.urban.org/sites/default/files/publication/86691/reforming_sentencing_and_corrections_policy_final.pdf http://www.justreinvest.org.au/wp-content/uploads/2018/11/Maranguka-Justice-Reinvestment-Project-KPMG-Impact-Assessment-FINAL-REPORT.pdf CR03CH15_Sabol ARjats.cls December 3, 2019 16:39 Kuziemko I. 2007. Going off parole: how the elimination of discretionary prison release affects the social costs of crime. Work. Pap. 13380, National Bureau of Economic Research, Harvard, MA. https://www.nber. org/papers/w13380.pdf Kuziemko I. 2014. How should inmates be released from prison: an assessment of parole versus fixed- sentencing regimes. Q. J. Econ. 128:371–424 Kyckelhahn T. 2012. State corrections expenditures, FY 1982-2010. Bur. Justice Stat. Rep. NCJ 239672, US Dep. Justice, Washington, DC LaVigne NG, Samuels J, Bieler S, Mayer D, Pacifici L, et al. 2013.The Justice Reinvestment Initiative: Experiences from the States, Washington, DC: Urban Inst. LaVigne NG. 2014. Lessons from the states: responsible prison reform. The Urban Institute. https://www.urban.org/sites/default/files/publication/23076/904631-Lessons-from-the- States-Responsible-Prison-Reform.PDF LaVigne NG, Bieler S, Cramer L, Ho H, Kotonias C, et al. 2014. Justice reinvestment initiative: state assess- ment report. Rep. 412994, Urban Inst., Washington, DC: https://www.urban.org/sites/default/files/ publication/22211/412994-Justice-Reinvestment-Initiative-State-Assessment-Report.PDF Lawrence A. 2008. State sentencing and corrections legislation: 2007 action, 2008 outlook. Rep., Natl. Conf. State Legis., Washington, DC. https://www.ncsl.org/print/cj/07sentencingreport.pdf Lowenkamp CT, Latessa EJ, Holsinger AM, 2006. The risk in action: What have we learned from 13,676 offenders and 97 correctional programs? Crime Delinquency. 52:77–93 Lowenkamp CT, Holsinger AM, Robinson CR, Cullen FT. 2012. When a person isn’t a data point: making evidence-based practice work. Fed. Probation. 76:11–20 Luna E, ed. 2017a. Reforming Criminal Justice: Punishment, Incarceration, and Release, Vol. 4. Phoenix, AZ: Ariz. State Univ. Luna E. 2017b. Mandatory minimums. See Luna 2017a, pp. 117–46 Lynch JP, Sabol WJ. 2001. Prisoner reentry in perspective. Rep., Urban Inst., Washington, DC. http:// webarchive.urban.org/UploadedPDF/410213_reentry.PDF Maruna S. 2011. Lessons for justice reinvestment from restorative justice and the justice model experience: some tips for an 8-year-old prodigy. Criminol. Public Policy 10:661–69 Mauer M. 2011. Sentencing reform: amid mass incarcerations—guarded optimism. Rep, Sentencing Proj, Washington, DC. https://www.sentencingproject.org/wp-content/uploads/2016/01/ABA- Sentencing-Reform-Amid-Mass-Incarcerations-Guarded-Optimism.pdf Mayer S, Patti FI. 2015. Beyond the numbers: toward a moral vision for criminal justice reform. Drake Law Rev. August:101–110 Natl. Assoc. State Budg. Office. (NASBO). 2002. State expenditure report 2001. Rep., NASBO, Washing- ton, DC. https://higherlogicdownload.s3.amazonaws.com/NASBO/9d2d2db1-c943-4f1b-b750- 0fca152d64c2/UploadedImages/SER%20Archive/nasbo2001exrep.pdf Natl. Assoc. State Budg. Office. (NASBO). 2017. State expenditure report: examining fiscal 2015–2017 state spending. Rep., NASBO, Washington, DC. https://higherlogicdownload.s3.amazonaws. com/NASBO/9d2d2db1-c943-4f1b-b750-0fca152d64c2/UploadedImages/SER%20Archive/ State_Expenditure_Report__Fiscal_2015-2017_-S.pdf Natl. Conf. State Legis. (NCSL). 2010. Significant state sentencing and corrections legislation 2007 and 2008. Rep., NCSL, Washington, DC. http://www.ncsl.org/research/civil-and-criminal-justice/ significant-state-sentencing-and-corrections-legis07.aspx Natl. Conf. State Legis. (NCSL). 2017. Statewide sentencing and corrections legislation. Rep., NCSL, Wash- ington, DC. http://www.ncsl.org/research/civil-and-criminal-justice/state-sentencing-and- corrections-legislation.aspx Office Justice Progr. (OJP). 2017. FY 2018 program summaries. Office Justice Progr. Rep., US. Dep. Justice, Washington, DC. https://ojp.gov/newsroom/pdfs/2018ojpprogramsummary.pdf Office Justice Progr. (OJP). 2018. FY 2019 performance budget. Office Justice Progr. Rep., US. Dep. Justice, Washington, DC. https://www.justice.gov/jmd/page/file/1034426/download Office Justice Progr. (OJP). 2019. FY 2020 performance budget. Office Justice Progr. Rep., US. Dep. Justice, Washington, DC. https://www.justice.gov/file/1144566/download www.annualreviews.org • Justice Reinvestment 337 A nn u. R ev . C ri m in ol . 2 02 0. 3: 31 7- 33 9. D ow nl oa de d fr om w w w .a nn ua lr ev ie w s. or g A cc es s pr ov id ed b y C ar ne gi e M el lo n U ni ve rs it y on 0 4/ 05 /2 1. F or p er so na l us e on ly . https://www.nber.org/papers/w13380.pdf https://www.urban.org/sites/default/files/publication/23076/904631-Lessons-from-the-States-Responsible-Prison-Reform.PDF https://www.urban.org/sites/default/files/publication/22211/412994-Justice-Reinvestment-Initiative-State-Assessment-Report.PDF https://www.ncsl.org/print/cj/07sentencingreport.pdf http://webarchive.urban.org/UploadedPDF/410213_reentry.PDF https://www.sentencingproject.org/wp-content/uploads/2016/01/ABA-Sentencing-Reform-Amid-Mass-Incarcerations-Guarded-Optimism.pdf https://higherlogicdownload.s3.amazonaws.com/NASBO/9d2d2db1-c943-4f1b-b750-0fca152d64c2/UploadedImages/SER%20Archive/nasbo2001exrep.pdf https://higherlogicdownload.s3.amazonaws.com/NASBO/9d2d2db1-c943-4f1b-b750-0fca152d64c2/UploadedImages/SER%20Archive/State_Expenditure_Report__Fiscal_2015-2017_-S.pdf http://www.ncsl.org/research/civil-and-criminal-justice/significant-state-sentencing-and-corrections-legis07.aspx http://www.ncsl.org/research/civil-and-criminal-justice/state-sentencing-and-corrections-legislation.aspx https://ojp.gov/newsroom/pdfs/2018ojpprogramsummary.pdf https://www.justice.gov/jmd/page/file/1034426/download https://www.justice.gov/file/1144566/download CR03CH15_Sabol ARjats.cls December 3, 2019 16:39 O’Hear M. 2017. The Failed Promise of Sentencing Reform. Santa Barbara, CA: Praeger Orszag PR. 2009. Memorandum to the heads of departments and agencies. Office Manag. Budg. Rep. M-10- 01, US Dep. Justice, Washington, DC. https://www.whitehouse.gov/wp-content/uploads/2018/ 10/m10-01.pdf Parks E, Cramer L, Flynn A, Love H, Ross C. 2016. Local justice reinvestment: strategies, outcomes, and keys to success. Rep. 2000903, Urban Inst., Washington, DC Petersilia J. 2014. California prison downsizing and its impact on local criminal justice systems. Harv. Law Policy Rev. 8:327–58 Pew. 2018. 35 states reform criminal justice policies through justice reinvestment: legislative action aims to increase public safety return on corrections spending. Rep., Pew Charit. Trusts, Washington, DC. https://www.pewtrusts.org/en/research-and-analysis/fact-sheets/2018/07/35-states-reform- criminal-justice-policies-through-justice-reinvestment Pfaff J. 2016. The complicated economics of prison reform. Mich. Law Rev. 114:951–81 Pfaff J. 2017. Locked In: The True Causes of Mass Incarceration and How to Achieve Real Reform. New York: Basic Books Porter ND. 2017. State advances in criminal justice reform, 2016. Rep., Sentencing Proj., Washington, DC. https://www.sentencingproject.org/wp-content/uploads/2017/01/State-Advances-in-Criminal- Justice-Reform-2016-1.pdf Robinson L. 2017. Statement before the subcommittee on commerce, justice, science & related agencies, committee on appropriations. US House Represent., Washington, DC Sabol WJ, Couture H, Harrison PM. 2007. Prisoners in 2006. Bur. Justice Stat Rep. NCJ 219416, Office Justice Progr., Washington, DC. https://www.bjs.gov/content/pub/pdf/p06.pdf Sampson RJ, Loeffler C. 2010. Punishment’s place: the local concentration of mass incarceration. Daedalus 139:20–31 Sherman L, Farrington DP, Welsh BC, MacKenzie DL, eds. 2012.Evidence-Based Crime Prevention. New York: Routledge. Rev. ed. Spelman W. 2009. Cash, crime, and limited options: explaining the prison boom.Criminol.Public Policy 8:29–77 Stemen D, Rengifo AF. 2011. Policies and imprisonment: the impact of structured sentencing and determinate sentencing on state incarceration rates, 1978–2004. Justice Q. 28:174–201 Stemen D, Rengifo AF. 2012. Charting the evolution of structure and determinacy in state sentencing and corrections policies 1970–2010. Justice Res. Policy 14:1–46 Stern V, Allen R. 2007. Localism and criminal justice: suggestions for a new balance between national and local decision making. See Allen & Stern 2007, pp. 43–55 Stoll M, Raphael M. 2013. Why Are So Many Americans in Prison? New York: Russell Sage Subramanian R, Delany R. 2014. Playbook for change? States reconsider mandatory sentences. Rep., Vera Inst. Justice, New York. https://storage.googleapis.com/vera-web-assets/downloads/Publications/ playbook-for-change-states-reconsider-mandatory-sentences/legacy_downloads/mandatory- sentences-policy-report-v3.pdf Subramanian R, Moreno R. 2014. Drug war détente? A review of state-level drug law reform, 2009–2013. Rep., Vera Inst. Justice, New York. https://storage.googleapis.com/vera-web-assets/downloads/ Publications/drug-war-détente-a-review-of-state-level-drug-law-reform-2009-2013/legacy_ downloads/state-drug-law-reform-review-2009-2013-v5.pdf Taxman FS. 2013. 7 keys to “make EBPs stick”: lessons from the field. Fed. Probat. 76:76–85 Taxman FS, Pattavina A, Caudy M. 2014. Justice reinvestment in the United States: an empirical assessment of the potential impact of increased correctional programming on recidivism. Vict. Offenders 9:50–75 Tonry M. 2011. Making peace, not a desert: penal reform should be about values not justice reinvestment. Criminol. Public Policy 10:637–49 Tonry M. 2017. Community punishment. See Luna 2017a, pp. 187–204 Tonry M, Nagin DS, eds. 2017.Crime and Justice, Vol. 46: Reinventing American Criminal Justice. Chicago: Univ. Chicago Press Travis J, Western B, Stevens Redburn F. 2014. The Growth of Incarceration in the United States: Exploring Causes and Consequences. Washington, DC: Natl. Acad. Press 338 Sabol • Baumann A nn u. R ev . C ri m in ol . 2 02 0. 3: 31 7- 33 9. D ow nl oa de d fr om w w w .a nn ua lr ev ie w s. or g A cc es s pr ov id ed b y C ar ne gi e M el lo n U ni ve rs it y on 0 4/ 05 /2 1. F or p er so na l us e on ly . https://www.whitehouse.gov/wp-content/uploads/2018/10/m10-01.pdf https://www.pewtrusts.org/en/research-and-analysis/fact-sheets/2018/07/35-states-reform-criminal-justice-policies-through-justice-reinvestment https://www.sentencingproject.org/wp-content/uploads/2017/01/State-Advances-in-Criminal-Justice-Reform-2016-1.pdf https://www.bjs.gov/content/pub/pdf/p06.pdf https://storage.googleapis.com/vera-web-assets/downloads/Publications/playbook-for-change-states-reconsider-mandatory-sentences/legacy_downloads/mandatory-sentences-policy-report-v3.pdf https://storage.googleapis.com/vera-web-assets/downloads/Publications/drug-war-d�tente-a-review-of-state-level-drug-law-reform-2009-2013/legacy_downloads/state-drug-law-reform-review-2009-2013-v5.pdf CR03CH15_Sabol ARjats.cls December 3, 2019 16:39 Tucker S, Cadora E. 2003. Ideas for an open society: justice reinvestment. Rep., Open Soc. Found., New York. https://www.opensocietyfoundations.org/uploads/f44e9fba-e56c-4adf-b686-b0cc95de442a/ ideas_reinvestment.pdf US Census Bur. 2019. Annual survey of state government finances. Rep., US Census Bur., Washington, DC: United States Census Bureau. https://www.census.gov/programs-surveys/state.html Welsh-Loveman J, Harvell S. 2018. Justice reinvestment initiative data snapshot: unpacking reinvestment. Rep. 98361, Urban Inst., Washington, DC West HC, Sabol WJ, Greenman SJ. 2010. Prisoners in 2009. Bur. Justice Stat. Rep. NCJ 231675, Office Justice Progr., Washington, DC Western B. 2018. Homeward: Life in the Year after Prison. New York: Russell Sage Whitehead PR, Ward T, Collie RM. 2007. Time for a change: applying the good lives model of rehabilitation to a high-risk violent offender. Int. J. Offender Ther. Comp. Criminol. 51:578–98 Wong K, Fox C, Albertson K. 2014. Justice reinvestment in an “age of austerity”: developments in the United Kingdom. Vict. Offenders 9:76–99 www.annualreviews.org • Justice Reinvestment 339 A nn u. R ev . C ri m in ol . 2 02 0. 3: 31 7- 33 9. D ow nl oa de d fr om w w w .a nn ua lr ev ie w s. or g A cc es s pr ov id ed b y C ar ne gi e M el lo n U ni ve rs it y on 0 4/ 05 /2 1. F or p er so na l us e on ly . https://www.opensocietyfoundations.org/uploads/f44e9fba-e56c-4adf-b686-b0cc95de442a/ideas_reinvestment.pdf https://www.census.gov/programs-surveys/state.html CR03_TOC ARI 1 November 2019 12:28 Annual Review of Criminology Volume 3, 2020 Contents The Discipline Engineer to Operations Research to Criminology: Quite a Trajectory Alfred Blumstein � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � 1 Control Theories Social Control Theory: The Legacy of Travis Hirschi’s Causes of Delinquency Barbara J. Costello and John H. Laub � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � �21 Self-Control and Crime: Beyond Gottfredson & Hirschi’s Theory Callie H. Burt � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � �43 Neighborhood and Spatial Processes Advances in Spatial Criminology: The Spatial Scale of Crime John R. Hipp and Seth A. Williams � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � �75 Broken Windows, Informal Social Control, and Crime: Assessing Causality in Empirical Studies Charles C. Lanfear, Ross L. Matsueda, and Lindsey R. Beach � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � �97 Gentrification, Land Use, and Crime John M. MacDonald and Robert J. Stokes � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � 121 Contexts of Violence and Offending The Social Organization of Sexual Assault Shamus Khan, Joss Greene, Claude Ann Mellins, and Jennifer S. Hirsch � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � 139 Prison Culture, Management, and In-Prison Violence John Wooldredge � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � 165 Learning from Criminals: Active Offender Research for Criminology Volkan Topalli, Timothy Dickinson, and Scott Jacques � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � 189 Criminalization and Punishment Processes The Intergenerational Transmission of Criminal Justice Contact Christopher Wildeman � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � 217 A nn u. R ev . C ri m in ol . 2 02 0. 3: 31 7- 33 9. D ow nl oa de d fr om w w w .a nn ua lr ev ie w s. or g A cc es s pr ov id ed b y C ar ne gi e M el lo n U ni ve rs it y on 0 4/ 05 /2 1. F or p er so na l us e on ly . CR03_TOC ARI 1 November 2019 12:28 Wrongful Convictions Brandon L. Garrett � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � 245 Mass Probation from Micro to Macro: Tracing the Expansion and Consequences of Community Supervision Michelle S. Phelps � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � 261 Parole Release and Supervision: Critical Drivers of American Prison Policy Kevin R. Reitz and Edward E. Rhine � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � 281 The Rise, Fall, and Afterlife of the Death Penalty in the United States Carol S. Steiker and Jordan M. Steiker � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � 299 Justice and Policing Justice Reinvestment: Vision and Practice William J. Sabol and Miranda L. Baumann � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � 317 Conceptualizing Policing and Security: New Harmscapes, the Anthropocene, and Technology Cameron Holley, Tariro Mutongwizo, and Clifford Shearing � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � � 341 Errata An online log of corrections to Annual Review of Criminology articles may be found at http://www.annualreviews.org/errata/criminol A nn u. R ev . C ri m in ol . 2 02 0. 3: 31 7- 33 9. D ow nl oa de d fr om w w w .a nn ua lr ev ie w s. or g A cc es s pr ov id ed b y C ar ne gi e M el lo n U ni ve rs it y on 0 4/ 05 /2 1. F or p er so na l us e on ly . work_cfkwynqts5cpjel7xsnmcnph64 ---- Technology and Justice (George Grant) ©, 1989 Howard R. Woodhouse Ce document est protégé par la loi sur le droit d’auteur. L’utilisation des services d’Érudit (y compris la reproduction) est assujettie à sa politique d’utilisation que vous pouvez consulter en ligne. https://apropos.erudit.org/fr/usagers/politique-dutilisation/ Cet article est diffusé et préservé par Érudit. Érudit est un consortium interuniversitaire sans but lucratif composé de l’Université de Montréal, l’Université Laval et l’Université du Québec à Montréal. Il a pour mission la promotion et la valorisation de la recherche. https://www.erudit.org/fr/ Document généré le 5 avr. 2021 22:20 Paideusis Technology and Justice (George Grant) Howard R. Woodhouse Volume 3, numéro 1, 1989 URI : https://id.erudit.org/iderudit/1073406ar DOI : https://doi.org/10.7202/1073406ar Aller au sommaire du numéro Éditeur(s) Canadian Philosophy of Education Society ISSN 0838-4517 (imprimé) 1916-0348 (numérique) Découvrir la revue Citer ce compte rendu Woodhouse, H. (1989). Compte rendu de [Technology and Justice (George Grant)]. Paideusis, 3(1), 18–19. https://doi.org/10.7202/1073406ar https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ https://apropos.erudit.org/fr/usagers/politique-dutilisation/ https://www.erudit.org/fr/ https://www.erudit.org/fr/ https://www.erudit.org/fr/revues/paideusis/ https://id.erudit.org/iderudit/1073406ar https://doi.org/10.7202/1073406ar https://www.erudit.org/fr/revues/paideusis/1989-v3-n1-paideusis05660/ https://www.erudit.org/fr/revues/paideusis/ Book Reviews George Grant, Technology and Justice (Anansi: Toronto, 1986). 135 pages. Paperback: $8.95 · George Grant's death in September, 1988 put an end to his reflections upon technology, modernity, and the exclusion of Platonism and even Chris- tianity from the modem world. As a Canadian philosopher, Grant raised fun- damental questions about these matters that are peculiarly our own. Neverthe- less, he did so in ways that evoke early traditions of Western thought whose language and ontology may seem quite alien to the modem reader. Technology and Justice, Grant's last book, is a collection of six essays on technology, faith and the multiversity, Nietzsche, research in the humanities, euthanasia, and abortion. They are all in a fundamental sense educational but it is upon 'Faith and the Multiversity' that I shall concentrate, since it is the book's central essay1 and most clearly concerned with formal education. The question that Grant asks is this: how is it possible for those who have faith to live in the multiversity where the dominant paradigm of knowledge, namely modem science, separates the process of knowing from that of loving? If, at the core of the modem university, there is a radical separation between intelligence and love, what meaning does Simone Weil's conception of faith as the experience of intelligence enlightened by love have (p. 38)? Clearly, the reductionist methods of science, its concern for objective knowledge, and in- strumentalist urge to dominate nature exclude the possibility of faith in Weil's sense. It is these aspects of science and their impact upon the university that leads Grant to refer to that institution as fundamentally divided, a multi-versity (p. 37).2 . Grant is deeply concerned about all of this because he takes Weil to have understood the foundations of faith most clearly. Like her, he believes the unity of intelligence/reason and love to underlie the most profound of human ex- periences and, in order to illustrate their fundamental unity, appeals to Plato's Republic, where the search for knowledge is identified wit,h the process of loving (pp. 72-73). Grant suggests two rays of hope that may prevent faith from being extin- guished from the multiversity. First, students and faculty may engage in reflec- tion that enables them to recall that the true, the good, and the beautiful are one. Unfortunately, such Platonic reflection is normally killed among students by the paradigm of modem science (p. 70). Second, western Christianity and modem science have both shared a desire to dominate the world. The arrogance of this position may be brought home to some in the multiversity who come to ap- preciate the emptiness at the core of modem science (p. 64 and pp. 76-77). Grant's hopes for a disenchantment with the paradigm of modem science and a turning towards faith appear forlorn. He was well aware of the power of the scientific paradigm but serious in his search for an alternative to the modem belief that human beings are distinctively free (pp. 74-75). He could not suc- cumb to the tenets of liberalism that we realise our freedom by making the world. as we want it, largely by means of modem science (pp. 57-61 and p. 65).3 18 Paideusis Was Grant correct to be so skeptical of modern thought? Two reasons suggest that he was not. First, there are .other kinds of reason than instrumental reason in the modem world. The work of the critical theorists, and particularly that of Jurgen Habermas, has shown that embedded in the Enlightenment project were also communicative and emancipatory reason based on shared norms and human needs that make possible non-instrumental views of human freedom. To the extent that the instrumental reason of modern science suppresses these shared norms and needs, it is to be criticised for hindering the advent of a more open and sharing society. Rather than turning back to Plato, the critical theorists articulate a critique of technology and science from within the assumptions of modemity.4 Second, a dialectical search for truth of this kind that poses human needs and their negation as the foundation of its critique surely has its roots in the Socratic method. Given the possibility of shared norms and expressed needs outside the paradigm of instrumental reason, the pursuit of truth need not be distinct from the search for the good and the beautiful. In this way the "modem experiment" is not as different from the Socratic enterprise as Grant supposes (p. 43), provided that it is not confined within instrumental reason. Grant was aware that he shared a common ground with those of us stand- ing within modernity but skeptical of technology and science, and particularly with those of us critical of U.S. imperialism. But he charted a different course that led him back to the Ancients in his quest for unity. His voice will be missed. Howard R. Woodhouse, University of Saskatchewan Notes 1 William Christian, ''Champion of Intellect in the Age of Technology'' The Globe and Mail, September 30, 1988. ' 2 George Grant, "The University Curriculum," Technology and Empire (Anansi Press, Toronto, 1969). ' 3 This was forcefully expressed in Grant's "In Defence of North America,'' ibid. 4 Jurgen Habermas, "Technology and Science as Ideology" Toward a Rational Society (Beacon Press, Boston, 1970). '. 3(1), (Fall)1989 19 work_cgbbncg2wrakzfdn5khlb7auxq ---- [PDF] Race, conventional crime, and criminal justice: The declining importance of skin color | Semantic Scholar Skip to search formSkip to main content> Semantic Scholar's Logo Search Sign InCreate Free Account You are currently offline. Some features of the site may not work correctly. DOI:10.1016/S0047-2352(99)00025-2 Corpus ID: 1641380Race, conventional crime, and criminal justice: The declining importance of skin color @article{DeLisi1999RaceCC, title={Race, conventional crime, and criminal justice: The declining importance of skin color}, author={M. DeLisi and Bob Regoli}, journal={Journal of Criminal Justice}, year={1999}, volume={27}, pages={549-557} } M. DeLisi, Bob Regoli Published 1999 Psychology Journal of Criminal Justice Blacks in the United States are arrested, prosecuted, convicted, and incarcerated in numbers disproportionate to their percentage of the population. One explanation is that racial discrimination against Blacks pervades the American system of criminal justice. This study examined the nature and extent of racial discrimination in the criminal justice system by evaluating five propositions using data from extant literature. Little evidence was found to support the allegation that the criminal… Expand View via Publisher soc.iastate.edu Save to Library Create Alert Cite Launch Research Feed Share This Paper 32 CitationsBackground Citations 11 Results Citations 1 View All 32 Citations Citation Type Citation Type All Types Cites Results Cites Methods Cites Background Has PDF Publication Type Author More Filters More Filters Filters Sort by Relevance Sort by Most Influenced Papers Sort by Citation Count Sort by Recency A comment on racial discrimination in prisons in England and Wales W. Chui Sociology 2001 Save Alert Research Feed Black Supporters of the No-Discrimination Thesis in Criminal Justice Shaun L. Gabbidon, Kareem L. Jordan, Everette B. Penn, George E. Higgins Sociology 2014 6 View 1 excerpt, cites background Save Alert Research Feed Race, Ethnicity, Crime and Criminal Justice in Canada S. Wortley, Akwasi Owusu-Bempah Political Science 2012 11 Save Alert Research Feed Black and white differences in the perception of justice. D. Wiley Psychology, Medicine Behavioral sciences & the law 2001 9 Save Alert Research Feed The Affordable Hypothesis: Punitive beliefs, violent beliefs, and race Matt DeLisi Psychology 2001 11 Save Alert Research Feed The imprisoned nonviolent drug offender: Specialized martyr or versatile career criminal? Matt DeLisi Psychology 2003 27 Save Alert Research Feed Does neighborhood crime matter? A multi-year survey study on perceptions of race, victimization, and public safety Wonhyuk Cho, A. Ho Psychology 2018 4 Save Alert Research Feed Criminal careers behind bars. M. DeLisi Medicine Behavioral sciences & the law 2003 106 Save Alert Research Feed Criminal Careers Behind Bars D. Cohen, Brame Dean 2003 PDF View 1 excerpt, cites results Save Alert Research Feed Perceptions of the Canadian criminal justice system among Nigerians: Evidence from a local Church in Winnipeg, Manitoba Temitope B. Oriola, Charles T. Adeyanju Sociology 2011 2 View 1 excerpt, cites background Save Alert Research Feed ... 1 2 3 4 ... References SHOWING 1-10 OF 92 REFERENCES SORT BYRelevance Most Influenced Papers Recency Race and criminal justice R. Reiner Sociology 1989 30 Save Alert Research Feed Racial Disparities in the Criminal Justice System: A Summary J. Petersilia Psychology 1985 100 View 2 excerpts, references background Save Alert Research Feed Racial Politics, Racial Disparities, and the War on Crime M. Tonry Psychology 1994 87 Save Alert Research Feed THE MYTH OF A RACIST CRIMINAL JUSTICE SYSTEM William Wilbanks Brooks/Cole (a div. of Wadsworth Pub W. Wilbanks Political Science, Psychology 1986 260 View 2 excerpts, references background Save Alert Research Feed The Changing Forms of Racial/Ethnic Biases in Sentencing Marjorie S. Zatz Sociology 1987 258 View 2 excerpts, references background Save Alert Research Feed Juvenile Offenders: Prevalence, Offender Incidence, and Arrest Rates by Race D. Huizinga, D. Elliott Psychology 1987 136 View 1 excerpt, references background Save Alert Research Feed Race and Involvement in Common Law Personal Crimes. M. J. Hindelang Sociology 1978 399 Save Alert Research Feed Unequal Justice: A Question of Color C. Mann Sociology 1993 217 View 2 excerpts, references background Save Alert Research Feed Crime, Culture and Ethnicity T. Maden Psychology 1993 11 View 1 excerpt Save Alert Research Feed Race and imprisonment decisions in California. S. Klein, J. Petersilia, S. Turner Psychology, Medicine Science 1990 105 Save Alert Research Feed ... 1 2 3 4 5 ... Related Papers Abstract 32 Citations 92 References Related Papers Stay Connected With Semantic Scholar Sign Up About Semantic Scholar Semantic Scholar is a free, AI-powered research tool for scientific literature, based at the Allen Institute for AI. Learn More → Resources DatasetsSupp.aiAPIOpen Corpus Organization About UsResearchPublishing PartnersData Partners   FAQContact Proudly built by AI2 with the help of our Collaborators Terms of Service•Privacy Policy The Allen Institute for AI By clicking accept or continuing to use the site, you agree to the terms outlined in our Privacy Policy, Terms of Service, and Dataset License ACCEPT & CONTINUE work_ch3xut42afb7jljyaruypynzmq ---- The Geography of Justice: Assessing Local Justice in Colombia’s Post-Conflict Phase Introduction Over the last ten years in Colombia, there has been an increasing interest in studying the role of institutions relating to both the country’s economic development and the construction of democracy. According to substantial literature on the subject, institu- tions have a central role in democracy-build- ing. However, various parties question the dimensions of this role and the way it relates to other variables such as violence, culture, and the market (Acemoglu & Robinson 2012; González, Bolívar, & Vásquez 2003; Gutiérrez 2010; López 2010; Rodríguez & Portes 2012; Romero 2003). This article analyzes the role of state insti- tutions at the local level in Colombia. The focus is not on exploring national security or political regime issues (although these top- ics are mentioned), but rather on the impli- cations stemming from state incapacity or even deficiency in terms of the population’s rights. The argument goes as follows: popula- tions who live in the peripheral areas of Colombia, where state institutions are weak or non-existent, are permanently vulnerable to violations because they are not served by institutions that uphold their rights. These are not exceptional cases of communities lost in the national geography, but rather are part of a widespread rights violation. According to calculations presented in The Right to a State (Garcia Villegas and Espinosa 2013), the State is not present in 60 per cent García-Villegas, M and Espinosa, J R 2015 The Geography of Justice: Assessing Local Justice in Colombia’s Post-Conflict Phase. Stability: International Journal of Security & Development, 4(1): 41, pp. 1–21, DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.5334/sta.gc RESEARCH ARTICLE The Geography of Justice: Assessing Local Justice in Colombia’s Post-Conflict Phase Mauricio García-Villegas* and Jose Rafael Espinosa† This article combines descriptive empirical research with theoretical reflections to offer policy guidelines on what the role of local justice institutions in Colombia’s post-conflict phase should be. The article is divided into two parts. In the first, we present empirical evidence to illustrate the ways in which justice operates differently across the territory. In addition to illustrating these disparities, we also demonstrate the connection between these disparities and some phenomena relevant to understanding the Colombian conflict. Based on these findings, the second part of this article defines the state-building challenge confronted by the Colombian State during the post-conflict phase. Following this part, we propose a solution to this state-building challenge: the State must adopt a combination of efficacy and justice, and we provide guidelines on how a post-conflict justice system can operate to achieve that combination. * Professor at Universidad Nacional in Bogotá, Colombia; Fellow at Institute for Legal Studies at the University of Wisconsin-Madison; Founding Member of the Center for Law, Justice and Society-Dejusticia, Colombia mvillegas@wisc.edu † Associate Researcher at Center for Law, Justice and Society-Dejusticia; Graduate student at Harris School of Public Policy – University of Chicago, United States jespinosa@dejusticia.org stability http://dx.doi.org/10.5334/sta.gc mailto:mvillegas@wisc.edu mailto:jespinosa@dejusticia.org García-Villegas and Espinosa: The Geography of Justice Art. 41, page 2 of 21 of the national territory, an area that is inhab- ited by more than six million people. These people lack what Hannah Arendt called ‘the right to have rights’ – the right to live in a political community in which their rights are recognized and protected.1 The central state owes a historical debt to these people which must be paid and, from a constitutional point of view, represents a systematic and flagrant violation of citizen rights similar to (or possibly worse than) violations that the Constitutional Court’s jurisprudence defines as an ‘unconstitutional state of affairs.’ In The Right to a State we used the expres- sion ‘institutional apartheid’ to describe what is currently happening in broad areas of the national territory in which the State is unstable or non-existent. As a result, the population is affected by the fact that their rights are not recognized or protected. Although the situation does not correspond exactly to the origin of the word ‘apartheid,’ which is closely linked to the South African context, the book defends the idea that even though the situation in Colombia is differ- ent, the discriminatory effects are similar. Institutional abandonment of large portions of the country results in segregation of the people who live there. While in South Africa segregation was based on the prevalence of one race over another, in Colombia it is founded on the prevalence of some regions over others. In this article we answer the following question: given the current peace process between the Colombian Government and the guerrilla group, and given that eventual agreements from that process will effect an enormous institutional challenge in the peripheral regions of Colombia, how can the local state be strengthened in order to address that institutional apartheid? In addi- tion, what role does justice play in such an institutional strengthening plan? This article is divided into two parts. In the first, we present empirical evidence to illustrate the ways in which justice operates differently at the regional level. In addition to illustrating geographic disparities in that operation, we also demonstrate the con- nection between the disparity and some phenomena relevant to understanding the Colombian conflict. Based on these findings, the second part defines the state-building challenge confronted by the Colombian State. We defend the idea that in order to confront this challenge, the State must adopt a combination of efficacy and justice, and we provide guidelines on how a post-conflict justice system should operate. The performance of (formal) local justice In this first part, we present the results of an empirical investigation that demonstrates the disparate functioning of (formal) justice in the country. We constructed an indicator on local justice performance that evaluates both presence and efficacy of formal justice institutions. Presence This first section evaluates the presence of justice representatives in the Colombian regions. It is a formal measurement that takes into account the presence of justice representatives in the territory and gives an idea of the geographic distribution of judges in Colombia, but it does not judge the effi- cacy or efficiency of their presence. The following Map 1 shows the distribu- tion of judges in the Colombian territory in July 2012, taking into account the popula- tion and size of the municipality.2 In order to address the dispersion of the data, we grouped municipalities based on their differ- ences from the national average.3 In this case, the municipalities ‘without data’ are non- municipalized and their jurisdiction is the responsibility of neighboring municipalities. As this Map 1 shows, the presence of judges is concentrated in the center of the country, plus two small niches: in the north around Cartagena and Barranquilla, and in the south in Pasto and the surrounding area. The presence of justice representatives should not only be analyzed in terms of quantity, but also in terms of quality. The García-Villegas and Espinosa: The Geography of Justice Art. 41, page 3 of 21 Map 1: Presence of Judges. Source: Superior Judicial Council (Consejo Superior de la Judi- catura – CSJ), National Administrative Statistics Department (Departamento Administrativo Nacional de Estadistica - DANE), Agustin Codazzi Geography Institute (Instituto Geografico Agustin Codazzi– IGAC) (2012). García-Villegas and Espinosa: The Geography of Justice Art. 41, page 4 of 21 Colombian State created the justice career track to guarantee the quality of justice rep- resentatives. In theory, only the best judges occupy public positions and rarely is (e.g. in the case of temporary licenses) the office occupied by provisional judges. The justice career track mechanism also serves to guar- antee the judges’ independence with respect to political representatives and other judges. This political independence is due to the fact that provisional representatives are named directly by the magistrates of their respective hierarchical superior tribunal.4 The judicial career track – similar to many public policies – has had a different impact in the various regions. We constructed a database of the provisional nature of judicial offices in the country based on information collected from administrative courts of the sectional judicial councils.5 The following Map 2 illustrates how pro- visionality is distributed across the country. This map demonstrates two notewor- thy aspects of the way in which the justice career track operates in Colombia. First, the justice career track does not function in a great part of the territory. According to information provided by the sectional judicial councils, temporary judges occupy 31 per cent of justice posts.6 In regional terms, the percentage of all provisional judges is equal to or greater than 80 per cent in 425 municipalities (from a total of 1103). Second, the map shows that provi- sionality is not randomly distributed across the country. As in previous maps, provision- ality – associated as much with a lack of merit as with the risks of clientelism – tends to concentrate in peripheral municipalities. Efficacy Second, we measure the efficacy of the jus- tice system at the regional level, understood as the system’s capacity to reach expected objectives. We limit ourselves to the efficacy of the criminal system for two reasons: first, the efficacy of criminal justice (as opposed to civil justice, for example) is a good indicator of state capacity to confront other social actors who compete for the monopoly on the use of force (Garcia-Villegas 2008); sec- ond, the criminal system is the only process- ing system in Colombia to offer a modicum of trustworthy information about its own management.7 In addition, we are focusing on the justice system’s efficacy in sanctioning homicides that occurred in each municipality. There are three reasons why we focus exclusively on homicides. First, they are the most seri- ous crimes and as such should be prioritized in judicial processing. Second, homicides are the most registered of crimes (as it is more difficult for a homicide to go unnoticed than a scam, for example). Finally, by limiting our- selves to homicide, we dodge an objection that could be made about our indicator, that is, whether the desirable result of processing is always a sentence. For some crimes, such as stealing a carton of milk, this is a point of discussion in judicial and criminal policy debates, as well as in the philosophy of law. In the case of homicides, however, the attor- ney cannot avoid formulating a charge, nor the judge a sentence, because of the serious- ness of the crime. To measure the performance of justice, we have therefore constructed an ‘efficacy rate.’ This indicator measures the percentage of cases entered into the system for which a sen- tence is formulated. In addition, when evalu- ating the number of sentences compared to the total entries, it takes into account the magnitude of the justice demand in the municipality.8 It is necessary to make three methodo- logical clarifications before moving on to the results. First, of the total municipalities, those for which there is a lack of complete information (number of entries, formulation of charges, and formulation of sentences), or those whose information suggests that there was an error (e.g. more sentences than charges or entries) were excluded. This reduced the number of municipalities from 1103 to 848. García-Villegas and Espinosa: The Geography of Justice Art. 41, page 5 of 21 Map 2: Provisional Nature of Justice Offices. Source: Sectional judicial councils (Consejos sec- cionales de la judicature) (2013). Authors’ own calculations. García-Villegas and Espinosa: The Geography of Justice Art. 41, page 6 of 21 Second, due to the availability and quality of information, we limited ourselves exclu- sively to criminal processes under the accu- satory penal system (Law 906 of 2004). For each municipality, we added existing infor- mation from the system’s period of validity, and based the efficacy analysis on informa- tion for each municipality. 9 Third, we measured the level of efficacy in the sanction of homicides that took place in a determined municipality. This does not nec- essarily mean that the criminal process took place in that municipality. Instead, it means that we are not measuring justice that physi- cally operates there, but rather justice that is effectively applied there. This does not repre- sent a problem for the research. We are inter- ested more in measuring the extent to which the system fulfills its purpose in the territory than in physical institutional presence. Map 3 shows the spatial distribution of the efficacy indicator.10 As the map shows, ‘high’ and ‘very high’ efficacy tends to concentrate in the depart- ments of Huila, Casanare, Tolima, the cof- fee region, to a lesser extent in Antioquia, Cundinamarca, Boyacá, Santander, and a few municipalities in Bolivar and Atlántico. Meanwhile, ‘low’ and ‘very low’ efficacy is concentrated in Nariño, Putumayo, Casanare, Meta, Vichada, Chocó, southern Córdoba, Catatumbo, southern Bolívar, and La Guajira. The majority of municipalities with ‘low’ and ‘very low’ efficacy are in corridors that share various features including: i) presence of armed groups; ii) areas of illegal crops; iii) areas of input transport for the produc- tion of cocaine; iv) presence of illegal mining; and v) low quality of institutions. The most noteworthy trait of the map is that these fac- tors operate in a context of local-level judi- cial inefficacy, which allows these activities to continue at low criminal cost. These maps do not always allow for defini- tive conclusions to be made about the insti- tutional capacity in a municipality. There are situations in which the justice and munici- pal government indicators are very good, but a more detailed analysis of the context, the history, and the internal power relations of the municipality show that institutional power only appears strong. For example, the department of Casanare – an example of institutional seizure or ‘coopted reconfigu- ration of the State’ – seems to have strong justice indicators, but in reality, they are not as strong as might be expected (Garay, De León, & Salcedo, 2010; García Villegas & Revelo Rebolledo, 2010; Hellman, Jones, & Kaufmann, 2000). The performance of local justice Until now, this paper has examined how the justice system’s presence and efficacy in the prosecution of homicides are distributed. Based on this analysis, we constructed a global indicator of local justice performance, taking these two dimensions into account. The indicator is composed of two variables: presence of judges and an efficacy rate for each municipality. The indicator includes a scale from 0 to 100, where 100 corresponds to the highest score and 0 to the lowest. This score was obtained by weighting the qualifications from the two components of the index,11 assigning a weight of 60 per cent to efficacy and 40 per cent to presence. We made this methodological decision because we believe that even though presence is an important dimension of justice, in many municipalities this presence is more nominal than real – just because there is a judge in a munici- pality does not mean that he/she imparts justice. This was one of the conclusions of Judges without a State (García-Villegas 2008). In this sense, a municipality with fewer judges who are more effective would be preferable to one with more judges who are less effective. The different possible scores of the index are grouped into five categories, which cor- respond to the five levels of local justice per- formance (see Annex 1). The Table 1 shows how the municipalities at different levels of the index are distributed. García-Villegas and Espinosa: The Geography of Justice Art. 41, page 7 of 21 Map 3: Efficacy. Source: AGO (Fiscalía General de la Nación). Authors’ own calculations. García-Villegas and Espinosa: The Geography of Justice Art. 41, page 8 of 21 As Table 1 shows, the majority of munici- palities (356) are distributed in the medium level of local justice performance.12 The low- est category is comprised of 136 munici- palities, a number greater than that of the two highest categories put together: 97 municipalities are in the ‘high’ category while 20 are in the ‘very high’ category. The table also shows a noteworthy result: with respect to the national average, more than a third of the municipalities of the country (375 of 848) have ‘low’ or ‘very low’ levels of performance. The following Map 4 shows these munici- palities spatially distributed by category. This map highlights patterns seen in previous maps. The municipalities with ‘medium,’ ‘high,’ and ‘very high’ levels of performance are found mainly in the center of the country, and to a lesser extent in the Caribbean Coast, Valle del Cauca, and the departments of Meta and Casanare. On the other hand, the municipalities with ‘low’ or ‘very low’ levels of justice perfor- mance tend to be located in the peripher- ies, especially in the departments of Nariño, Chocó, Putumayo, Caquetá, and Vichada. In Córdoba, Magdalena, Atlántico, and Sucre the ‘low’ and ‘very low’ performance of jus- tice coincides with the most southern areas of the departments, which are characterized by difficult access, floods and challenging transport channels which isolate the munic- ipalities from regional centers. Different expressions of local justice performance in the territory Justice does not operate in isolation in a municipality. On the contrary, its perfor- mance is related to the context in which the everyday workings of the justice system take place. This section analyzes the relation- ships between the local justice performance indicator and various socio-economic and violence-related variables that we thought relevant. We are interested in identifying differences when comparing the justice indicator with these other variables in dif- ferent categories of the municipality. We can thereby observe that municipalities with a ‘low’ or ‘very low’ level of local justice per- formance present similar behavior in other institutional dimensions. The disparate per- formances of justice are related to the exist- ence of coca crops, forced displacement, presence of illegal armed groups, percentage of Afro-Colombians, and percentage of indig- enous people.13 Graph 1 illustrates the relationship between the average density of coca crops in a group of municipalities and local jus- tice performance.14 The difference in crops between the five categories of local justice performance (very high, high, etc.) is strik- ing. Municipalities catalogued with ‘low’ and ‘very low’ performances in terms of local justice have an average of twelve per cent and thirteen per cent crop density respec- tively (in other words, on average twelve to thirteen per cent of each square kilometer in these municipalities is dedicated to coca crops), while in other municipalities the density does not go above two per cent. The performance of justice is weak where the density of coca crops is greater. This does not necessarily mean that in municipalities with a very low justice per- formance there is more drug trafficking than in other municipalities. There are sim- ply more crops. The differences in forced displacement15 between different categories of justice are quite large, as seen in Graph 2. The Level Number of municipalities % Municipalities Very low 136 16% Low 239 28% Medium 356 42% High 97 11 % Very high 20 2 % Total 848 100 % Table 1: Municipalities by levels of local jus- tice performance. García-Villegas and Espinosa: The Geography of Justice Art. 41, page 9 of 21 Map 4: Local justice performance. Source: SJC/AGO, own calculations. García-Villegas and Espinosa: The Geography of Justice Art. 41, page 10 of 21 municipalities with very low local justice per- formances have more than double the rate of displacement when compared to those clas- sified in the other four categories. The statis- tical results allow us to conclude that a lower level of local justice performance implies a greater number of displaced people. The results found in relation to the coca crop dynamics and to displacement are convincing and reveal two facets of the Colombian armed conflict. On the one hand, the results allow for the identification of one of the illegal armed groups’ greatest eco- nomic sources, and on the other, they reflect the vulnerability of rights generated by the conflict. Tragically, local justice is weaker in areas with more coca crops and where dis- placement rates are greater. These trends gave notable results. In gen- eral, municipalities with ‘high’ and ‘very high’ levels of justice performance had a lesser presence of illegal armed groups. In Graph 1: Density of crops and levels of local justice performance. Source: SIMCI 2012; Authors’calculations. Graph 2: Average displacement rate by categories of local justice performance. Source: Vice President’s Office 2005–2011. Authors’ calculations. García-Villegas and Espinosa: The Geography of Justice Art. 41, page 11 of 21 municipalities with very high justice per- formance rates there was no paramilitary or BACRIM (bandas criminales, former paralim- itary groups) presence from 2000 to 2012. The guerrilla presence comprised almost a quarter of the overall presence of illegal armed groups in municipalities of ‘medium’ justice performance rates and almost a fifth of the presence of illegal armed groups with ‘low’ or ‘very low’ performance rates. In terms of guerrilla presence, there is a clear negative relationship: the greater the local justice performance, the lower the num- ber of years of guerrilla presence. In terms of paramilitary and BACRIM presence, the result is different, because the municipali- ties with weaker justice rates are different from those municipalities who experienced the presence of these groups for a greater number of years. Except in municipalities with high levels of justice performance, the paramilitaries and the BACRIM were present no matter the institutional justice capac- ity. In general terms, whereas the guerrillas aim to fight against the State, the paramili- taries appropriate or strategically use the State (García Villegas & Revelo Rebolledo 2010; López 2010; Romero 2003; 2007). It is also worth noting that the BACRIM pres- ence is greater than that registered by the paramilitaries, which suggests that the demobilization process did not reduce, but rather increased, the presence levels of these groups in the municipalities, as illustrated in Table 2. These two results allow us to argue that the presence of the guerrilla tends to congre- gate in municipalities with weaker justice, while the paramilitaries or the BACRIM have a more homogenous presence in municipali- ties, regardless of their justice performance levels. This coincides with results shown in previous research (García-Villegas 2008). The bias in guerrilla presence and relative homogeneity in paramilitary and BACRIM presence allows us to address each group’s process of capturing institutions (or not). The guerrillas have skirted to the periphery of the country, where institutions are weaker, while the paramilitaries have managed to stay in important urban areas where they have used justice to achieve their military and eco- nomic objectives. In terms of ethnic composition, there are important differences between the five categories of the local justice index. Municipalities with ‘very low’ justice perfor- mance levels have greater levels of indig- enous and Afro-Colombian people. Graph 3 shows that municipalities located in the low- est justice category have an average of 16 per cent and thirteen per cent of Afro-Colombian and indigenous populations respectively, while in other justice categories the popula- tion does not rise above nine per cent and six per cent respectively. The municipalities with a very low level of justice performance have greater numbers of displaced people, greater hectare den- sity of coca crops, and a greater number of Category of justice Number of years with illegal groups presence 2000–2012 Guerrilla Paramilitaries (2000–2006) BACRIM (2007–2012) Very high 1.3 0 0 High 2.9 1.03 1.8 Medium 4.2 1.68 2.69 Low 5.3 1.66 2.3 Very low 5.1 1.4 2.3 Table 2: Presence of illegal armed groups broken down in years between 2000 and 2012. García-Villegas and Espinosa: The Geography of Justice Art. 41, page 12 of 21 indigenous and Afro-Colombian people in their population. A similar phenomenon occurs in terms of the presence of the guer- rilla groups, which is found less often in municipalities with ‘high’ and ‘very high’ lev- els of justice performance. From Institutional Apartheid to the Constitutional State: Local Justice in the Post-Conflict Phase Political institutions in Latin America are embedded in a social and institutional context much different from the modern European state model, which the Latin American countries have inherited. This has, in part, resulted in the common dispar- ity between norms and social realities that has characterized Colombian institutional life since time immemorial. The existence of the modern state can be claimed when the fulfillment of three conditions or basic characteristics occurs: efficacy, legality, and legitimacy (Bobbio 2005). The State in Latin America has deficiencies in each one of these three characteristics. For example, state effi- cacy is not always attained legitimately and, on occasion, the legitimate state is incapable of presenting itself to powerful individuals and groups, be they legal or illegal. These situations are particularly common in certain spaces, generally (but not exclusively) located in the periphery of the national territory. Based on a constructivist, tiered, and prag- matic vision of known state institutions (García-Villegas 2014; Migdal 2011; Portes & Smith 2010; Rodríguez & Portes 2012), we will now try to respond to the following question: how can public policy address the enormous challenge of incorporating un- institutionalized areas of the country into the social rule of law? What path must be taken to respond to this challenge?16 This question is even more relevant today as Colombia faces a post-conflict phase in which opportunities to carry out historic reforms will present themselves, as a result of the eventual peace agreements. In effect, the draft agreements published until recently imply large-scale social, economic, and politi- cal development initiatives in the periphery of Colombia. In concrete terms, the agree- ments foresee large-scale rural reforms, an increase in political participation, and the elimination of drug trafficking. To apply these eventual agreements, however, there must exist local institutions with the capacity Graph 3: Percentage of Afro-Colombians and indigenous people by municipality by category of local justice performance. Source: Dane 2012. Authors’ calculations. García-Villegas and Espinosa: The Geography of Justice Art. 41, page 13 of 21 to implement the public policy necessary to enforce the objectives of the agreements. The design of these institutions and public policies is still to be defined and will be the subject of intense debate in years to come. Discussions on the post-conflict phase often assume that these peripheral areas already have the institutional capacity to implement the agreements, which is not true. Until now, discussions on transitional jus- tice in Colombia have focused mainly on the dilemma between justice and peace. That is, how to resolve the tension between the need for accountability by those ultimately responsible for crimes, and the need to com- promise with these actors so that they aban- don weapons and enter politics. This debate, though fundamental, has been restricted to a limited definition of justice. It under- stands justice exclusively as the prosecution of those responsible or the guarantee of the rights of the victims, and ignores the need for justice dedicated to resolving daily con- flicts that present themselves in transitional areas. This is problematic because it ignores the objective of social peace, a post-conflict goal closely related to the success of the tran- sition. For the post-conflict phase, we have to think not only about the kind of justice we implement to deal with those respon- sible from all sides of the conflict, but also about which institutions will be required to consolidate peace in the regions through the resolution (formal and/or informal) of social conflicts. In order to respond to these questions, we first look at three features of the modern state that were mentioned at the beginning of The Right to the State: efficacy, legality, and legitimacy. Which path should we take, in institutional terms, to arrive at an efficient, legitimate, and legal state? Given that the legitimacy of the consti- tutional state is attained through legality and protection of citizen rights, here we propose the concept of ‘lega-timacy’ which involves and coordinates both purposes (legality and legitimacy). We assume that the constitutional state or, more precisely, the social rule of law, pursues two fundamen- tal or interdependent objectives: 1) efficacy, and 2) ‘lega-timacy.’17 Each of the two axes in the following graph (horizontal and vertical) represent the two objectives mentioned in a continuum from low to high. Based on these two axes, it is possible to compare and contrast the differ- ent scenarios featuring state institutions, as shown in the following graph. Types of Institutions The graph above demonstrates the wide range of possible scenarios, from extreme institutional weakness to extreme state authoritarianism, passing through the social rule of law (ROL), which possesses a type of contained strength. This graph also illus- trates how the vulnerability of many sectors of the population can originate not only in the excess of state power but also in its defi- cit. The constitutional state is therefore both an effective and a contained power. The ideal scenario is represented in the upper right, where there is a maximum of both variables. ROL is found there, with a greater degree of efficacy and legitimacy.18 At the other end of the spectrum – the lower left – we find the opposite of ROL – extremely weak institutions with little ‘lega-timacy.’ This area represents institu- tional apartheid (among other situations), García-Villegas and Espinosa: The Geography of Justice Art. 41, page 14 of 21 a situation characterized by vulnerability and discrimination against the population. Not all of what falls under this area of extreme instability can be characterized as institu- tional apartheid, due to the fact that not all institutional weakness implies a severe degree of discrimination. For example, in some isolated areas inhabited by indigenous communities, institutional incapacity is sup- planted by strong community cohesion. The two intermediate cases are explained in the following way: the first, in the upper left, combines a maximum of ‘lega-timacy’ with a minimum of efficacy. This situation is more theoretical than real, given that it is dif- ficult to conceive of a society under a nominal state (that has no power) and in which events occur in a legal and legitimate way (except perhaps something close to anarchism). In the far lower right we find authoritarian institutions in which a maximum exercise of power is combined with minimum ‘lega- timacy.’ This type of state maintains peace and imposes order within the territory, and is able to guarantee certain rights. However, it does so without legitimacy or legality. Many attempts to bring the State to the Colombian periphery have been reduced to the creation of this type of state. It should also be added that these are extreme cases and that, as the graph shows, it is possible to imagine intermediate cases (in fact, the Latin American and urban ver- sions of ROL, in general terms, could be cat- egorized as in the upper right square, but at a point close to the center of the graph). It is also important to acknowledge that it is not always easy to spatially identify each case. Here, we have said that institutional apart- heid is a common phenomenon in the geo- graphic periphery of the country. However, this phenomenon exists in the cities, in mar- ginalized neighborhoods and rural areas that we could call internal peripheries, where the social rule of law is relatively strong. In addition, it is important to note that institutional apartheid is not always apparent and easy to detect. There are cases in which legality, and some legitimacy, are found in regions where institutions have been cap- tured or coopted by armed or illegal actors. This is the case of the mafia-state, which not only adopts the appearance of legality, but also defends and operates with the law while distorting its meaning and using legality to favor illegality. It is even possible that in these cases, the population is overtaken. This is an example of a state outside of constitu- tional order, which nevertheless follows its judicial forms and routines. It also conceals institutional capture which results in domi- nation and oppression, perhaps worse than that of the authoritarian state. We therefore return to the question with which we began this final section. How can we transition from an institutional apartheid state to ROL? We have identified five paths, each one of them represented by a line that unites extreme institutional weakness to ROL. The first of them, path A (the gray continuous line) is defended by military regimes in Colombia and Latin America, and conceives of the con- stitutional challenge as a task that starts and ends with pacification of the territory, as the imposition of order without legitimacy. This path is not only unacceptable from an ethical and legal point of view (as it sacrifices the rights of one part of the population to improve the conditions of the rest), but also from an empirical point of view. Experience shows that there is no guarantee that this option will be successful. Indeed, the imposi- tion of force without human rights, democ- racy, or control instead seems to reproduce violence and institutional weakness in the Latin American context. The second path, B (in dotted gray), pro- poses to reach both objectives of ROL but based on sequential logic in which efficacy comes first. This path seeks to pacify the territory first (expelling or defeating the enemy) and then, only when this objec- tive has been achieved, concerns itself with the legality and legitimacy of the State. The National Territorial Consolidation Plan García-Villegas and Espinosa: The Geography of Justice Art. 41, page 15 of 21 adopted by the national government seems to have adopted this model (García Villegas & Espinosa Restrepo 2012; Palou 2011). Once pacification is achieved, a transition from military to civilian government is realized. The protection of the citizen is of the utmost importance in this transition. Finally, when this protection is consolidated, the third phase of stabilization begins and economic, social, and institutional development can be consolidated. Although path B is attractive from a mili- tary standpoint and in terms of creating order, it has been demonstrated as non- conducive – and even counterproductive – to the creation of ROL. In many cases, this first stage of military domination translates to serious human rights violations. The third path, C, originates in a logic contrary to the others. Instead of prioritiz- ing efficacy, this path emphasizes legitimacy. This path consists of introducing institu- tional reforms with evident legitimacy in social environments characterized by institu- tional crisis. The expectation is that popular support for the new institutions will result from these reforms, and combined with their intrinsic legitimacy, will serve to strengthen state institutions. This perspective inspired some of the institutional designs defined by the 1991 Constitution, in particular, those related to decentralization and citizen par- ticipation mechanisms (Gutiérrez 2010; Sánchez & Chacón 2006). This path is a type of ‘democratism’ according to which demo- cratic routines are enough to achieve social rule of law. This assumes that democratic legitimacy could remedy weaknesses in insti- tutional capacity through the passage of time and with the help of popular mobiliza- tion. However, after more than twenty years of implementing the Constitution, the limits and even dangers of this view have become evident. It is not only probable that ‘lega- timacy’ did not bring efficacy in these areas but that even worse, new democratic institu- tions were captured and corrupted by crimi- nal organizations (García Villegas & Revelo Rebolledo 2010; Gutiérrez 1996, 2010b; López 2010). It is worth noting the affirma- tion of Albert Hirschman (1977) according to whom, ‘not all good things come together.’ The fourth path, D (see the continuous line), supposes that it is possible to simulta- neously construct all three levels of the ROL building. This is the best path from the per- spective of constitutional axiology (García Villegas & Uprimny 1999). In practice, how- ever, the situation poses many difficulties. This path is feasible in territories in which the State is more nominal than effective and in which there is no competition from another armed actor. However, what hap- pens when the State finds itself in a territory occupied by an armed actor that imposes its law on inhabitants? In these cases, the first task of the State consists of gaining military control and monopoly on the use of force in the area. This is what the international litera- ture widely recommends: in the construction of the State, security must be prioritized, but with legality (Fukuyama 2004; Jensen 2008; Ottaway 2002; Rubin 2008). Opening mech- anisms of broadened political participation without consolidating a minimum of efficacy has translated to an increase in violence. The literature, however, falls short of indicating how to achieve this ideal combination of security and legality. How can this minimum of security be achieved within the constitu- tional framework? Perhaps the response to this question would be the creation of a fifth path, denoted as E. Path E would recognize the practical need for sequencing between the two objectives pursued (efficacy and legality / legitimacy), but would condition its success on the effec- tive presence of the justice system in this transition. We have stated previously that in Colombia, we must try to achieve three features of ROL at the same time. This is a normative ideal that should be maintained. However, in prac- tice, absolute concomitance is frequently a difficult goal to achieve. This is due to the fact that there is a conditionality on these García-Villegas and Espinosa: The Geography of Justice Art. 41, page 16 of 21 factors.19 Path E endeavors to respond to this difficulty. It demands that military action tar- geting the reduction of armed actors in the territory is accompanied by strong judicial control directed at the protection of funda- mental rights of those who live in the terri- tory in which the military operations take place. Some aspects of the other objective (‘lega-timacy’), such as broadened citizen participation, social investment, or the exer- cise of representative democracy, could be temporally different but always under the vigilance and control of the justice system. In this way, path E paves the way to a type of spatially and temporally exceptional state. In the literature on state-building in transi- tional contexts, state formation is always pre- sented as a process whose objective consists of creating an effective state that imposes itself on powerful actors who question its power. This means that in general, it collides with the objective of achieving an institu- tional framework characterized by legitimacy and legality. The National Consolidation Plan, formed some years ago in Colombia with the idea of bringing the State to periph- eral territories affected by the armed con- flict, seems to obey this supposition (García Villegas & Espinosa Restrepo 2012; Palou 2011). However, the collision between these two objectives is not inevitable. Our hypoth- esis is that the strengthening of local justice can serve as a bridge for the concomitant achievement of both purposes. Our hypothesis is supported by the fact that justice has the ability to ‘domesticate’ the force necessary for the State to impose itself on armed actors who operate in an area. In this process of the domestication of force, justice provides legitimacy to the State imperium. It is improbable that in this early stage, all expressions of the social rule of law are present. The defense of social rights or participatory democracy, for exam- ple, requires a degree of institutional devel- opment that it is not possible to achieve in those initial moments. However, nothing impedes justice from accompanying this first state intervention. This is not only possible but also limits the use of force and submits the coercive power of the State to the consti- tution and the law. Justice has strong links to the two sides of the tension that we have been analyzing – efficacy and ‘lega-timacy.’ On the one hand, it moderates the force of efficacy by sub- mitting the State’s need to impose itself on enemies to legal requirements. On the other hand, by avoiding the violation of human rights through the use of force, justice has a legitimizing effect on state action. This effect comes not only from the legality imposed by justice, but also from the democratic char- acter of judges and from the fact that they are defenders of the constitution and of law, which are essentially democratic normative parameters. In addition, the judge not only provides legitimacy to the state-building process, but also offers efficacy by contributing to the overcoming of social conflicts. When a con- flict must be mitigated, state intervention should target the pacification of social rela- tionships. In that sense, a justice system that manages to resolve daily conflicts (like neigh- borly issues, or property claims, etc.) also helps to construct the social fabric necessary for the State to operate normally. In a post- conflict phase, one of the first steps should be to establish successful conflict resolution mechanisms. To conclude, we would like to note (albeit tentatively, as this topic requires greater research and reflection) that local justice in the post-conflict phase needs at least four conditions to achieve its proposed objectives. First, justice-related public policy should adopt a regional focus. Colombia is a socially, culturally, and geographically complex coun- try, which requires a similarly area-specific approach to policy. Justice-related public policy should take local justice demands into account, as well as institutional capac- ity, cultural traditions, the legacy of con- flict, and geographic space. Regional studies must be conducted to identify these justice García-Villegas and Espinosa: The Geography of Justice Art. 41, page 17 of 21 demands (frequent conflicts, motivation to adopt different models, etc.) and, depending on these needs and contextual limitations (institutional, cultural, economic, etc.), spe- cific policy should be adopted in response to the demand. The ‘one size fits all’ approach should be replaced by a focus on multiple sizes and models that integrate Colombia’s regional diversity. Path E is therefore not an immobile path. By combining efficacy with ‘lega-timacy,’ the path can in some cases be closer to the axis of efficacy while in others be closer to that of ‘lega-timacy.’ Second, a regional focus on justice requires modifications to the center of jus- tice administration – the central state – in Bogota. Colombian justice is too inbred, and lacks technical competency and account- ability. The Judicial Council should be more plural, open, and managerial in order to be more democratic, accountable, and thereby more legitimate in the eyes of the citizenry. In addition, the evaluation and design of pol- icy should have its technical foundations in quantitative and qualitative data. Third, the abilities of judges who work in peripheral areas must be strengthened. Justice administration has traditionally sent judges with the least knowledge and expe- rience to the peripheral areas of the coun- try, particularly in conflict-ridden areas. However, the opposite should occur, as it is precisely those locations that need the most able judges who can contend with difficult problems. In addition to the creation of new offices and positions, a new incentive system must be established to stimulate qualified people to work in these regions. In addition, the justice system should employ managers, psychologists, sociologists, social workers, and others who are essential in identifying and addressing conflicts in an efficient and effective way. Fourthly, the term ‘justice system’ should be understood broadly. This is a corollary of the points above. The system’s institutional capacity must be strengthened (conditions 2 and 3) but with a regional focus (condition 1). This implies that it is possible to conceive of local justice institutions that are not exactly the same as those that operate in the capi- tal of the country. The debate between for- mal and informal justice could thereby be overcome by a harmonious collaboration between the two. The justice system should allow for justice standards and informal local procedures (giving equal responsibility to local leaders or conciliators) that are both democratic and efficient, to continue operat- ing and resolving conflicts. In these cases, the task will consist of coordinating standards and procedures with other state entities.20 We believe that a justice system that adopts these four principles can usefully serve as a hinge between two objectives that can be contradictory in conflict contexts: building peace and building the State. The challenge consists in creating innovative policies that brings the four principles together. We believe this to be possible only when a constructivist vision of the problem is adopted, and when there exists a fair medium between favoring all contexts and realities (and saying that the law should adapt to reality) and imposing an ideal vision of justice without reservations. Competing Interests The author declares that they have no com- peting interests. Funding Statement Part of this research was funded by The Kingdom of the Netherlands. Notes 1 Arendt had v ictims of totalitarian states in mind (1982). However, the vulner- ability that characterizes the absence of the right to have rights also occurs when there is no institutional presence or when institutions are captured by ille- gal actors. Dignity and other rights are at risk when the State is too strong or too weak – when it acquires totalitarian traits or when it loses its capacity to uphold rights. García-Villegas and Espinosa: The Geography of Justice Art. 41, page 18 of 21 2 To control for differences in population and extension of territory, we calcu- lated an indicator of presence by mak- ing the municipalities equal, assuming that all have 100,000 inhabitants and are 100km.2 We also focused on low- hierarchy judges who should be present in the entire territory no matter the size of the municipality. 3 We built categories based on the average, and on distances with respect to the aver- age in standard deviation units. 4 It is important to take into account the variable of institutional design. The mag- istrate election system favors the forma- tion of ‘roscas’ or chains of sycophantism in the judicial branch, in addition to a lack of accountability. Tribunal magis- trates are elected by magistrates in the high courts based on lists compiled by the Administrative Court of the Superior Council (whose members are elected, in turn, by the high courts). This ‘rosco- grama’ or sycophantic network is repro- duced at the local level due in part to the provisional nature of some offices. Given that tribunal magistrates directly name provisional judges, there is a higher risk of reproduction of the network in areas with high rates of provisionality. 5 We understand ‘provisional’ to be any judicial office that – for a variety of reasons – is not occupied by a repre- sentative assigned to the post by virtue of the judicial career track. We do not include decongestion offices because by definition, they tend to be occupied by provisional representatives and do not exist in all parts of the country. 6 If the number of decongestion offices is included, the statistic is even more alarm- ing, because the percentage of provi- sional justice posts at the national level increases to 39 per cent. 7 The first stage in this research consisted of compiling all statistical information available, and conducting the first inves- tigation of how different entities in the judicial branch collect and systematize information. Unfortunately, at the end of this first stage, we concluded that we could not use information from the Superior Judicial Council about entries and exits for different types of processes (admin- istrative, ordinary, criminal, disciplinary) because the data collection methods were not very trustworthy. We therefore chose to use information from the SPOA, the Attorney General’s Office’s information system which, although it has some weak- nesses, is the least problematic of all. 8 The formula we used was as follows: ( )i i i i Total sentences Total entries Total sentences Total entries - - . This equation provides a cluster of val- ues on a scale of −1 to 1 as results, in which −1 represents the municipalities where there was not even one sentence passed for all of the cases entered. 1 rep- resents the municipalities in which there were sentences for all of the entries, and 0 represents municipalities in which sen- tences were made for half of the entries. For more information about the con- struction of the indicator, see the work of Leopoldo Fergusson, Juan Fernando Vargas, and Mauricio Vela, from which we took the idea about formulation (Fergusson, Vargas & Vela 2013). 9 This allows us to control the fact that the criminal accusatory system has become valid gradually over the territory. 10 It is important to note that the categories we used to group the municipalities were constructed based on the results that the municipalities had in the indicator, not on the maximum results possible. In no municipality of Colombia were more than 40 per cent of entered cases sen- tenced between 2005 and 2011. 11 The formula we used was the following: ( ) ( ) 0.6 100,000 0.4 i i i i i i i Number of judges Total population i Total sentences Total entries Total sentences LJI Total entries Extension æ ö- - ÷ç ÷= ç ÷ç ÷çè ø æ ö´ ÷ç ÷ç ÷+ ç ÷ç ÷ç ÷÷çè ø García-Villegas and Espinosa: The Geography of Justice Art. 41, page 19 of 21 We normalized and redefined the pres- ence indicator on a scale from 0 to 100. The corrected efficacy indicator, which previously went from −1 to 1, was also recoded on a scale from 0 to 100. 12 This is of course due to the way we con- structed the indicator, which groups municipalities according to how different they are from the average. 13 The variables of coca crops and forced displacement show the municipal aver- age of each variable between 2005 and 2011, with the goal of making a homo- geneous comparison with the justice indicator. The source on coca crops is the registry conducted annually by the UNODC through the Integral Illegal Crop Monitoring System. The displacement data come from the journal of the Vice President’s Office and correspond to the number of displacements according to the municipality from which the person was expulsed. The presence of illegal groups comes from a database created by the CERAC (Restrepo, Spagat & Vargas 2006). The period of the variable is 2000 to 2012. For the presence of paramilitar- ies and BACRIM, two different periods were analyzed: for the paramilitaries, from 2000 to 2006 and for the BACRIM, from 2007 to 2012. The illegal mining data are the product of research by the People’s Ombudsman’s Office three years ago (2010). The data on indigenous and Afro-Colombian people come from the 2005 census created by the DANE. 14 To calculate the quantity of illegal crops in a municipality, values were taken from 2005 to 2011 and the average was found. Density corresponds to the relationship between cultivated hectares and coca per kilometer squared. A crop density value of 12 hectares per square kilometer means that in this area 12 per cent of each kilo- meter is used for coca cultivation. 15 The rate of displacement per 100,000 inhabitants in the period 2005–2011 was taken as a reference. 16 Balakrishnan Rajagopal (2008) has stron- gly criticized the discourse on ‘rule of law’ as a strategy for the construction of insti- tutions in the post-conflict phase. In gen- eral terms, he sustains that the discourse on ‘rule of law’ is seen as a technical, judicial, apolitical discourse that ends up being useful to escape the political dis- cussion. When people appeal to this dis- course, they hide contradictions between different public policy agendas, such as development and human rights agendas, or security and human rights, which can- not be resolved simply by invoking the ‘rule of law’ as a mantra. The discourse on the ‘rule of law’ hides commitments that should be made between these agendas in order to reach these valid goals. We believe that this criticism is true but does not necessarily imply that the discourse should be abandoned. Rather, it should be conceptualized and examined for specific tensions that could be found in its interior. We accept Rajagopal’s invi- tation to break down what we under- stand by ‘rule of law’ and accept – even if not completely – the tensions between efficacy, legitimacy, and legality in the Colombian case. 17 It is also worth noting that, analytically, legality and legitimacy are two different things. See Bobbio (2005) and Ost and van de Kerchove (2001). 18 Some Scandinavian countries are close to this case (Munck 2009). 19 It is possible to have an effective state (here we adopt a minimal, almost Hobbesian, concept of efficacy and as a result, we are not referring to administra- tive or governmental efficacy) that is nei- ther legitimate nor legal. There can also be a legal state with deficiencies in terms of legitimacy, but it is not possible to find a situation in which democracy and legality exist without an effective state. There can of course exist a lack of all ele- ments, as in areas dominated by armed actors who challenge the State, where García-Villegas and Espinosa: The Geography of Justice Art. 41, page 20 of 21 there is no democratization or protec- tion of rights. Someone could state that armed actors, when they impose order and security, are guaranteeing rights. However, we dismiss this possibility and sustain that law cannot be guaranteed by illegal means. 20 A recent report indicates that the FARC have begun to cede their guerrilla justice administration system to the community action boards (JAC by its Spanish acro- nym) of the areas where they have influ- ence (2015). It would be an error for the State to impose upon the JAC justice sys- tem without first evaluating its strengths and weaknesses, and considering ways to coordinate it with more formal justice procedures. References Acemoglu, D and Robinson, J 2012 Why Nations Fail. The Origins of Power, Prosper- ity and Poverty. New York: Crown Business. Bobbio, N 2005 Teoría general de la política. Madrid: Trotta. Fergusson, L, Vargas, J F and Vela, M 2013 Sunlight Disinfects? Free Media in Weak Democracies. Bogotá: Uniandes. Fukuyama, F 2004 State-building: Govern- ance and World Order in the 21st Century. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Garay, L J, De León, I and Salcedo, E 2010 Captura y Reconfiguración Cooptada del Estado en Guatemala, México y Colombia. Análisis conceptual de las memorias de la Primera Discusión Internacional sobre Captura y Reconfiguración Cooptada del Estado. Bogotá: Grupo Método. García-Villegas, M 2008 Jueces sin Estado. Bogotá: Siglo del Hombre – Dejusticia. García-Villegas, M 2014 La eficacia sim- bólica del derecho. Sociología política del campo jurídico en América Latina. Bogotá: Random House. García Villegas, M and Espinosa Restrepo, J R 2012 Incorporación institucional de la periferia en Colombia: descentralización, regalías y el Plan Nacional de Consoli- dación. Bogotá: Dejusticia. García Villegas, M and Revelo Rebolledo, J 2010 Estado alterado. Clientelismo, mafias y debilidad institucional en Colombia. Bogotá: Dejusticia. García Villegas, M and Uprimny, R 1999 El nudo gordiano de la justicia y de la guerra en Colombia. In Camacho, A & Buitrago, F L (Eds.), Armar la paz es desarmar la guerra. Bogota: IEPRI, CEREC, FESCOL, pp. 33–70. González, F, Bolívar, I and Vásquez, T 2003 Violencia política en Colombia. De la nación fragmentada a la construcción del Estado. Bogotá: CINEP. Gutiérrez, F 1996 Dilemas y paradojas de la transición participativa. Análisis Político, 29: 43–64. Gutiérrez, F 2010 Instituciones y territorio: la descentralización en Colombia. In 25 años de la descentralización en Colom- bia. Bogotá: Konrad Adenauer Stiftung, pp. 11–54. Hellman, J, Jones, G and Kaufmann, D 2000 Seize the State, Seize the Day: State Capture, Corruption and Influ- ence in Transition by Joel Hellman, Geraint Jones, Daniel Kaufmann. Wash- ington D.C.: The World Bank. Available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers. cfm?abstract_id=240555 DOI: http:// dx.doi.org/10.1596/1813-9450-2444 Jensen, E G 2008 Justice and the Rule of Law. In: Call, C T & Wyeth, V (Eds.) Build- ing States to Build Peace. Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner Publishers, pp. 119–142. López, C (ed.) 2010 Y refundaron la patria . . . De cómo mafiosos y políticos reconfiguraron el Estado colombiano. Bogotá: Corporación Nuevo Arcoiris, Congreso Visible, Dejusticia, Grupo Método y MOE. Migdal, J S 2011 El Estado en la sociedad. Una nueva definición del Estado. (Para superar el estrecho mundo del rigor). In Estados Fuertes, Estados débiles. México: FCE, pp. 15–66 Munck, G 2009 Mesuring Democracy. Bal- timore: The Johns Hopkins University Press. http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=240555 http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=240555 http://dx.doi.org/10.1596/1813-9450-2444 http://dx.doi.org/10.1596/1813-9450-2444 García-Villegas and Espinosa: The Geography of Justice Art. 41, page 21 of 21 Ost, F and Van de Kerchove, M 2001 Ele- mentos para una teoría crítica del derecho. Bogotá: Universidad Nacional-Facultad de Derecho, Ciencias Politicas y Sociales. Ottaway, M 2002 Nation Building. Foreign Policy, 132: 16–24. DOI: http://dx.doi. org/10.2307/3183443 Palou, J C 2011 Balance de la Política de Consolidación a partir del estudio de 4 regiones intervenidas. Presented at the La Política de Consolidación Territorial del Estado Colombiano: evolución, desafíos, obstáculos y potencialidades, Bogotá. Portes, A and Smith, L 2010 Institutions and National Development in Latin America: A comparative Study. Socio- Economic Review, 1: 1–37. DOI: http:// dx.doi.org/10.1093/ser/mwq018 Rajagopal, B 2008 Invoking the Rule of Law in Post-Conflict Rebuilding: A Criti- cal Examination. William & Mary Law Review, 49: 1347–1376. Restrepo, J, Spagat, M and Vargas, J F 2006 The Severity of the Colombian Conflict: Cross-Country Datasets versus New Micro-Data. Journal of Peace Research, 43(1): 99–115. DOI: http://dx.doi.org/ 10.1177/0022343306059924 Rodríguez, C and Portes, A 2012 Las institu- ciones en Colombia; un análisis soci- ológico. Bogotá: Ediciones Uniandes. Romero, M 2003 Paramilitares y autodefen- sas 1982–2003. Bogotá: IEPRI. Romero, M (ed.). 2007 La ruta de la expansión paramilitar y los acuerdos políticos. Bogotá: Cerec – Corporación Nuevo Arco Iris. Rubin, B R 2008 The Politics of Security in Postconflict Statebuilding. In: Call, C T & Wyeth, V (Eds.), Building States to Build Peace. Boulder, Co: Lynne Rienner Pub- lishers, pp. 25–48. Sánchez, F and Chacón, M 2006 Conflicto, Estado y descentralización: del progreso social a la disputa armada por el control local, 1974–2002. In Gutiérrez, F & Sánchez, G (Eds.), Nuestra guerra sin nombre. Trans- formaciones del conflicto en Colombia. Bogotá: Norma – IEPRI, pp. 347–404. How to cite this article: García-Villegas, M and Espinosa, J R 2015 The Geography of Justice: Assessing Local Justice in Colombia’s Post-Conflict Phase. Stability: International Journal of Security & Development, 4(1): 41, pp. 1–21, DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.5334/sta.gc Published: 24 July 2015 Copyright: © 2015 The Author(s). This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 Unported License (CC-BY 3.0), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author and source are credited. See http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0/. OPEN ACCESS Stability: International Journal of Security & Development is a peer-reviewed open access journal published by Ubiquity Press. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/3183443 http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/3183443 http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/ser/mwq018 http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/ser/mwq018 http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0022343306059924 http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0022343306059924 http://dx.doi.org/10.5334/sta.gc http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0/ _GoBack work_chqejjomczc4thfbsghnp4dh4a ---- Egalitarian Justice and Expected Value Knight, C. (2013) Egalitarian justice and expected value. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice. ISSN 1386-2820 Copyright © 2013 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge The content must not be changed in any way or reproduced in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holder(s) When referring to this work, full bibliographic details must be given http://eprints.gla.ac.uk/76960/ Deposited on: 25 March 2013 Enlighten – Research publications by members of the University of Glasgow http://eprints.gla.ac.uk http://eprints.gla.ac.uk/76960/ http://eprints.gla.ac.uk/ http://eprints.gla.ac.uk/ 1 Egalitarian Justice and Expected Value* Carl Knight, University of Glasgow and University of Johannesburg I. Introduction The traditional form of egalitarianism is outcome egalitarianism, which proposes to equalize individuals’ advantage levels. Writers such as Ronald Dworkin (1981), G. A. Cohen (1989), and Richard Arneson (1989) rejected such views, pointing out that they would require that advantages are equalized even if some individuals have gratuitously lowered their advantage levels below the average. They instead proposed brute-luck egalitarianism, which is often described as having two parts: first, like outcome egalitarianism, it says that the differential distributive effects of brute luck, which defines the outcome of risks which are not deliberately taken, are unjust; and second, unlike outcome egalitarianism, it says that the differential distributive effects of option luck, which defines the outcome of deliberate gambles, are not unjust. This description of brute-luck egalitarianism is something of an oversimplification. It also includes a third part: it says that, where responsible choice is unmediated by luck, its results are not unjust. This third part is related to the second (option luck) part, as both involve choice, but is importantly different from it. This difference comes out where one contrasts a losing gamble with a predictably destructive act. If I lose my house in a gamble, I have been a victim of bad option luck, and brute- * This article is forthcoming (as of February 2013) in Ethical Theory and Moral Practice. The original publication is available at www.springerlink.com. 2 luck egalitarianism as it is usually understood supposes I am due no compensation. But compensation is similarly unforthcoming should I destroy my house in such a way that its loss is not mediated by luck. The distinction between results which flow directly from choices, and those which arise from a combination of choice and luck, is unimportant to both brute-luck egalitarians and outcome egalitarians, but for opposite reasons. For the brute-luck egalitarian, inequalities which follow directly from choice and those which arise as a matter of option luck are similarly just; for the outcome egalitarian, such inequalities are similarly unjust. But a third egalitarian position takes this distinction as crucial. All-luck egalitarianism identifies brute-luck inequalities as unjust, as do all forms of egalitarianism.1 Its innovation is to treat distributions which follow directly from choice as not unjust, while treating distributions which follow from differential option luck as unjust. 1 The term ‘all-luck egalitarianism’ is from Shlomi Segall (2010, ch. 3). Richard Arneson (2007; 1999, 490-91) has endorsed one form of all-luck egalitarianism and criticized another. John Roemer (1996, 276- 78; 1998, ch. 8) also appears to endorse a version of the view, apparently assuming, for instance, that an equal opportunity principle will pool risks among smokers. However, Roemer’s settled position leaves it up to society to decide which factors should be treated as potentially compensation-entitling, and hence he is best interpreted as agnostic on option luck. Larry Temkin (2011) and Alexander Cappelen and Ole Frithjof Norheim (2005) defend all-luck egalitarianism, though the latter do so without distinguishing it from the more common brute-luck egalitarianism. Peter Vallentyne (2002, 539-40) refers to the view as ‘equality of luck’. Interestingly, Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen (2005, 259) mentions a responsibility-insensitive form of all-luck egalitarianism. The argument of the present article leaves it open whether corrections for the results of option luck are due regardless of individuals’ responsibility for them, or because individuals cannot be held responsible for them. 3 To see the intuitive appeal of the view, consider again the difference between losing a house as a matter of option luck and losing it as the result of a predictably destructive act. Option luck is not present only in classic, casino-style gambles. Any kind of investment that might go up or go down is exposed to option luck and is thus a gamble in the relevant, extended sense. Many would feel compensation more appropriate for someone who lost their house as the result of an investment that was impaired by deteriorating market conditions, than for someone who lost their house by covering it in flammable liquid and throwing a lit match into it.2 All-luck egalitarianism responds to that difference of intuition. The main internal problem for all-luck egalitarianism is how to respond to cases of option luck. Where distributions have resulted from brute luck or directly follow from choices, all-luck egalitarianism has a simple solution – the brute luck is eliminated entirely, and the direct results of choice are allowed to stand. But where there is a responsible choice but with results that have been mediated by option luck, no simple solution of this sort is available. To undo the combined results of the choice and attendant luck altogether would fail to recognize the important role of choice, carrying the position too close to outcome egalitarianism. But equally, to allow the combined results of choice 2 It has been suggested to me that this case implicitly appeals to differences in intentionality between the house burner and the investor. But even where intentionality is constant, bad option luck appears to call for correction in a way that more straightforward results of choice do not. For instance, there seems a stronger case for (state) assistance to someone who has put their money in a savings account at a long-established bank that has unexpectedly collapsed, than there is for assistance to someone who has the same profit- making intention, but who has followed a strategy that is bound to fail (e.g. buying many lottery tickets and ‘reinvesting’ all winnings in more lottery tickets). 4 and luck to stand gives too much influence to luck, and indeed makes the position indistinguishable from brute-luck egalitarianism. This problem is pressing because, in practice, there are no or virtually no cases of acts wholly unmediated by luck.3 Even if I cover my house in flammable liquid, light a match, and throw it in, there is still something short of a 100 per cent chance of burning the house down: there is a small chance of the match extinguishing mid air, for instance. What drives all-luck egalitarianism is the thought that there is nevertheless an important difference between this case, and that in which I unluckily lose my house due to market conditions. The house burning case, though not a pure case of unmediated choice, is very close to one - perhaps there was a 99 per cent chance that my actions would result in the loss of the house. By contrast, making the investment might have only a one per cent chance of resulting in the loss of the house, in which case luck is very prominent in the outcome. What all-luck egalitarianism must do, then, is provide some account that puts these cases near opposite ends of a spectrum which runs from pure choice (implying zero compensation) to pure chance (implying full compensation). To capture this importantly scalar quality of all-luck egalitarianism, we can clarify that it treats distributions which follow from differential option luck as unjust, to the extent that they follow from differential option luck. But how can we measure the extent to which distributions follow from differential option luck? The most promising solution is to say that a distribution follows from differential option luck insofar as it is characterized by the unexpectedly good or bad outcomes of choice. Insofar as we are all-luck egalitarians, our aim is then to provide individuals with 3 I thank an anonymous referee for this point. 5 the expected value of their choices (Temkin 2011, 65). This accommodates the intuitive difference between house burning and investing on account of the fact that the former has a much lower expected value. Though this solution has appeal, it faces several questions which have, to date, not received much attention. First, should risks be pooled among gamblers alone, so only winning gamblers compensate losing gamblers with the expected value of their gambles, or should the entire community pool risks? Second, which kind of probabilities (for instance, objective or subjective) should be used to calculate expected values and thus fair shares? Finally, what should be done where resources are so scarce that gamblers cannot be provided with the expected value of their gambles? In this article I present a version of all-luck egalitarianism that provides a plausible account of these issues. Cast in this light, all-luck egalitarianism provides a valuable perspective on egalitarian justice. As this last claim suggests, an important limitation of the argument is that it focuses only on egalitarian justice, which is concerned with distributing benefits and burdens in such a way that equality is achieved in some substantive sense.4 Egalitarian justice contrasts with any parts of morality which are not matters of justice (for example, supererogation), any parts of justice which are not matters of distributive justice (for example, prohibition of physical attack), and any parts of distributive justice which are non-egalitarian (for example, promotion of overall advantage). My argument is then narrow in the sense that I claim only to show what is required in the name of equality. For that reason, I will simply disregard the common objection to all-luck egalitarianism 4 This was also the focus of the seminal presentations of brute-luck egalitarianism by Arneson (1989, 77) and Cohen (1989, 907, 909-11). For a specification of substantive equality see Knight 2009a. 6 that undoing the effects of option-luck inequalities would be deleterious of overall advantage levels (Segall 2010, 52-3; Barry 2008, 138 n. 7; Dworkin 2011, 358; Anderson 2008, 247-48). If there is more to distributive justice than equality, it may sometimes be all-things-considered just to allow option-luck inequalities to stand for the sake of increases in overall advantage, but that consideration has no place in an argument about the nature of equality. And my argument is narrower still, in that I focus on trying to work out the most plausible form of all-luck egalitarianism. While I suggest some attractions of this view, I do not engage in the sustained criticism of rival egalitarian views that would be required to establish all-luck egalitarianism as the all-things- considered most plausible version of egalitarianism. In what follows, the three aforementioned questions for all-luck egalitarianism are considered in turn. Section II argues that winning gamblers and non-gamblers alike should provide losing gamblers with the expected value of their gambles, and that more generally, risks should be pooled throughout the community. Section III argues that the appropriate sort of probabilities for assessing expected value are neither objective nor subjective, but rather the probabilities gamblers would be warranted to expect (except where they non-culpably lack the capacity to expect what is warranted). Section IV argues that, where there are insufficient societal resources to provide individuals with expected values, each individual’s entitlement is reduced by the same percentage as the overall shortfall. I then, in Section V, consider the objection that this form of all-luck egalitarianism allows risk-takers to impose externalities on non-risk-takers, and suggest that this objection actually points to a strength of the view. Section VI concludes. 7 II. Pooling All-luck egalitarianism is sometimes presented as requiring that ‘individuals who make the same choices should also have the same outcomes’ (Cappelen and Norheim 2005, 478). On this view, risks are pooled among those who make identical choices. While this serves to distinguish the view from brute-luck egalitarianism, it is evidently insufficiently determinate as a full statement of the view. Some fuller account of who indemnifies who is required. Writers who propose compensation for bad option luck without falling back on outcome egalitarianism have generally focused on expected value. Kasper Lippert- Rasmussen (2001) has claimed that, where gamblers would prefer the expected value of a gamble to facing the gamble itself, and thus are in his terms ‘quasi-gamblers’, there is a stronger case for redistribution from winning to losing gamblers. While taxation as a means of ‘ensuring that winners and losers alike end up with expected values of their gambles’ would disadvantage ‘gamblers proper’ (those who prefer the gamble over its expected value), similar taxation would improve the ex ante prospects of quasi-gamblers (Lippert-Rasmussen 2001, 555). A similar weight on the distinction between quasi- gambles and gambles proper is suggested by Marc Fleurbaey (2001), who explicitly suggests that quasi-gamblers are due the expected values of their gambles.5 And Nicholas 5 In later work Fleurbaey (2011, 86; see also Fleurbaey 2008) favours an ‘egalitarian-equivalent’ criterion, which, ‘[f]or any individual, ask[s] what level of external treatment (e.g. transfers) would maintain her current level of outcome if she had a reference (say, average) level of circumstance characteristics. Then give priority, in the sense of the maximin criterion, to those individuals with the least favourable level of external treatment in this counterfactual computation’. Whether this view compensates for bad quasi- 8 Barry (2008, 145-46) writes that, ‘to apply luck egalitarianism, we must calculate the impact of luck on each risk taker and act to ensure that the benefits and burdens associated with this luck are shared equally amongst them all’, subject to the condition ‘that redistribution should only occur when risk takers would prefer to share out the wins and losses associated with risk taking (via this redistributive scheme), than to let luck run its course’. All-luck egalitarianism as it is standardly understood pools risks among gamblers in this way, but drops Barry’s (and, perhaps implicitly, Lippert-Rasmussen’s and Fleurbaey’s) condition that the pooling occurs only among quasi-gamblers. In other words, all-luck egalitarianism extends the treatment Barry proposes for quasi-gambles to all forms of option luck – quasi-gambles and gambles proper alike. It seeks to give losing gamblers the expected values of their gambles, at the expense of winning gamblers. For instance, Shlomi Segall (2010, 45-6) suggests that all-luck egalitarianism ‘requires pooling the costs of medical treatment among those who make similar gambles with their health’. The view that risks should be pooled among gamblers in some way faces the grouping problem – that of deciding which groups of gamblers should share each other’s risks. The assumption seems to be that similar gambles should be pooled. But there is no apparent non-arbitrary way of grouping gamblers as sufficiently similar. As a referee commented, ‘[s]hould the skiers be bundled together with the mountaineers and the divers, or not? The farmers with the biotech startups?’. gambles or bad option luck generally will depend on whether they are classified as responsibility characteristics or circumstance characteristics. 9 Even if this problem could be overcome, it is not clear that pooling risks among gamblers alone is justified. It seems natural in the two categories of risk-taking on which the literature has focused to date.6 In the first category, the payoffs of each risk-taker are independent of those of other risk-takers. For instance, whether one smoker develops cancer is (usually) unaffected by whether other smokers develop cancer. In the second category, the payoffs of each risk taker are inversely correlated with those of other risk takers. For instance, casino gamblers can often only win to the extent that other casino gamblers lose. What these two categories of risk taking have in common is that the average payoff corresponds to the expected payoff (in the case of independent risks, this result is obtained for large numbers, as where we consider every smoker in a country). It follows that, in these cases, risk takers as a group are not unlucky. Thus, it seems obvious that if losing gamblers are due compensation, it should be at the expense of winning gamblers, as winning gamblers are, in these cases, necessarily lucky - they are the lucky members of a not unlucky group. Pooling among gamblers alone seems less appealing, however, when we consider a neglected third category of risk taking. Here the payoffs of each risk taker are positively correlated with those of other risk takers. Sometimes similar gambles, or even gambles in general, may all turn out very badly (or very well). Bookmakers generally benefit, and punters generally lose out, when football (soccer) matches are drawn. In the wider economy adverse weather conditions may result in crop failure, or currency movements may leave exporters without a market for their products. In such circumstances, compensating the losers of a losing group at the expense of the ‘winners’ of a losing 6 I owe this point to an anonymous referee. 10 group – transferring assets from the least unlucky farmers to the most unlucky farmers, say – is not enough to satisfy egalitarian justice. All members of the group have been disadvantaged relative to another group, that of non-risk-takers. Now it might be argued that this disadvantaging is through the fault or choice of risk-takers. After all, they have chosen to expose themselves to risk. But it does not seem to me that this is a coherent answer for the all-luck egalitarian. After all, they are, unlike brute-luck egalitarians, committed to saying that bad option luck is not a fair basis on which persons might be disadvantaged. If a person cannot fairly be disadvantaged relative to another because one has bad option luck and the other has good option luck, it is hard to see how a person might fairly be disadvantaged relative to another because one has bad option luck and the other has no option luck. Indeed, as Lippert-Rasmussen (2001, 562) notes, egalitarians ‘want to be able to tell whether an inequality between two persons is a matter of differential option luck’. If risks are pooled among gamblers alone, inequalities between gamblers and non-gamblers may well be due to option luck, which all-luck egalitarians should find objectionable. Given the possibility of positively-correlated risks, it seems plausible that compensation for losing gamblers should in principle be available not only from winning gamblers, but from non-gamblers as well. This also solves the grouping problem as it obviates the need to identify some smaller part of the general population as appropriately subject to pooling. I therefore construe all-luck egalitarianism as requiring pooling of risk not just amongst those subject to option luck, and insofar as they are subject to option luck, as would be the case if I simply extended Barry’s treatment of quasi-gambles to all option luck. Rather, risk is to be pooled amongst the community as a whole. Assuming 11 background equality, each individual is, provisionally, due the expected outcome of their choices, be they choices to expose oneself to option luck or choices to avoid option luck.7 Of course, as with individual gamblers, gamblers as a group will only be compensated insofar as they have actually suffered bad luck: if gamblers made choices with a low expected value there will typically be no unfairness in them being worse off than non- gamblers. Furthermore, when risk takers as a whole have good luck, they are required to transfer assets to non-risk takers. As the proposed view attempts to deliver expected values to individuals, it will try to minimize access to choices which create exposure to option luck, which breaks the link between individual holdings and expected values. On this construal, egalitarianism will recommend that gambling and similar practices be directly prohibited and/or have their option luck effects undone ex post. III. Probabilities The next task is to clarify the suggestion that all-luck egalitarianism responds to expected value.8 The expected value of a gamble is found by multiplying the (prudential or moral) value of each possible outcome by the probability of it occurring, and summing the results. The difficult question is which probabilities all-luck egalitarianism should use when assessing the expected value of a gamble. 7 I say ‘provisionally’ as this formula must be adjusted for cases of incapacity and scarcity; see below. 8 For discussion of the difficulty of combining accounts of expected value with non-compensation for option luck see Lippert-Rasmussen 2001, 566-70. 12 Basing judgments on subjective probabilities – the odds as actually assessed by the gambler – would be manifestly unfair, amounting as it would to rewarding over- confidence and penalizing under-confidence, characteristics which are not typically chosen by their bearers. But it would equally be unfair to base distributions on objective probabilities, as individuals might very well be ignorant of the odds through no fault or choice of their own.9 This is especially so considering that option luck encompasses not just gambles-proper with expected outcomes that are easily obtainable by mathematical means but also complicated quasi-gambles such as career choices. Essentially the same objection applies to a third possibility suggested by Lippert-Rasmussen (2001, 566) – that of responding to ideal subjective probabilities, which are what agents’ subjective probabilities would be under conditions of increased rationality and/or information. Individuals no more have access to ideal subjective probabilities than they do objective probabilities, and this may, again, be through no fault or choice of their own. We can, of course, avoid the problems with expected value by solely engaging in ex ante activities (in particular preventing gambles).10 But such a strategy would not minimize the influence of luck on distributions as some gambles would occur both prior to and under any prohibitionist regime. Some ex post activity (redistribution) will be required, and this needs to give a role to probabilities. My suggestion here is that all-luck egalitarianism refers to warranted probabilities adjusted for non-culpable incapacity. The core idea is that individuals 9 This unfairness may arise even where individuals are similarly ignorant; under such conditions they may understandably make different choices arbitrarily (see Vallentyne 2002, 536). 10 This point was made by Shlomi Segall (private communication). 13 should receive the outcomes they are warranted in expecting from the choices they make.11 An assessment of probabilities is warranted if, overall, the evidence available to the individual points towards that assessment.12 This is not to say that the individual actually does make that assessment of probabilities, nor need it be the case that that assessment of probabilities is factually correct. Warranted probabilities thus differ from both subjective probabilities and objective probabilities, while having some of the intuitive appeal of both. By making our egalitarianism respond to warranted probabilities we can take into account the epistemic limitations that the agent faces, as subjective probabilities promise, while insulating justice from epistemically indefensible beliefs, as objective probabilities promise.13 Of the previously mentioned probabilities, ideal subjective probabilities are the closest to warranted probabilities, but they differ in that warranted probabilities disregard any information not actually available to the agent, as seems fitting given that the agent may not be culpable for the missing information. Nevertheless, responding to unadulterated warranted probabilities may be troubling to the luck egalitarian. Some individuals may be incapable of assessing evidence appropriately. Some such individuals’ incapacities may have arisen from their choices, and they may have been warranted in expecting the incapacity and (on this prior occasion) capable of recognizing the warrant, in which case any resulting disadvantage 11 In some cases, two or more expectations may be (equally) warranted. In such cases it seems acceptable to use the mean expectation for distributive purposes. For simplicity I set aside cases of multiple warrant. 12 This formulation, and much else in this paragraph, draws on Robertson 2011. 13 The exact specification of when belief in a probability is warranted is not a task of a theory of justice. Just as luck egalitarians typically leave responsibility as a problem to be solved by metaphysicians, so I believe they should leave warrant as a problem to be solved by epistemologists. 14 appears unproblematic from a luck egalitarian perspective. But others may not have brought about their incapacity. For instance, they may have received a low standard of schooling, or they may have a lower than average natural intelligence (though not so low that they can be considered incapable of choice). It seems clear that the luck egalitarian can not allow individuals to be (dis)advantaged on account of brute luck differences in how they assess evidence.14 The all-luck egalitarian will, on my interpretation, have similar concerns about incapacities which are the upshot of bad option luck. For these reasons the core idea should be constrained thus: individuals receive the warranted probabilities of their choices except insofar as individuals’ inabilities to recognize which beliefs about probabilities are warranted have arisen through no fault or choice of their own. An inability has arisen through no fault or choice of its bearer insofar as it is (1) a matter of brute bad luck for the bearer and/or (2) the upshot of the bearer’s choice that the bearer was either (a) not warranted to expect or (b) warranted to expect but incapable of recognizing the warrant.15 Insofar as individuals are non-culpably 14 For an attempt to defuse the distributive effects of variations in individuals’ initial dispositions see Vallentyne 2008. 15 Hence one type of non-culpable incapacity is non-culpable on account of the fact that its bearer made a choice while non-culpably incapacitated, and that incapacity was non-culpable on account of the fact that its bearer made a choice while non-culpably incapacitated, and so on. This is not, of course, an infinite regress: each step must reflect an actual capacity-affecting choice a person has made while non-culpably incapacitated. 15 incapacitated their ‘choices’ are treated as a matter of luck, and individuals receive what they would have received had they made no choice.16 At one extreme, if an individual’s assessment of the outcome of a gamble is unwarranted, but this epistemic shortfall has come about through no fault or choice of their own, their fair share is unaffected by their choice. This is justified because it would be unfair for them to be disadvantaged (or, indeed, advantaged) through no fault or choice of their own, as they would be if warranted probabilities, which they did not and could not base their decisions on, were used to assess their fair share. At the other extreme, if it is either the case that an individual’s assessment of the outcome of a gamble is warranted, or unwarranted but wholly culpably so, their fair share is that which they were warranted to expect. This is justified because either the warranted probabilities coincide with the gamblers’ assessment, or because they fail to coincide but in such a 16 Peter Vallentyne (2011, 181) suggests the alternative position that, where individuals are not responsible for their false beliefs, ‘the presence of imaginary outcomes can, relative to the value of the foreseen impact, shrink the value for which the agent is responsible’. It is hard to see how these beliefs can have such a role within a responsibility-sensitive view without making some worse off than others through no fault or choice of their own. For instance, two individuals might make identical choices, one believing that it has moderately beneficial results, the other believing that it has only slightly beneficial results. If the choices are actually highly beneficial, Vallentyne’s position suggests that the first individual receives the moderate benefit that she anticipated but the second individual only receives the slight benefit that she anticipated (see Vallentyne 2011, 183-4). That the second individual more significantly underestimated the amount of benefit than did the first cannot be described as the former’s fault or choice, as she is, we assume, not responsible for her false belief. This suggests either that responsibility is not as Vallentyne describes, or that it is as Vallentyne describes, but that egalitarian justice does not always respond to responsibility. The position in the text is consistent with both stances. 16 way that, though the resulting distribution will be based on different probabilities than those used by the gambler, this divergence, and hence any difference of outcome, is the fault of the gambler. Many cases would fall between the extremes, as gamblers’ unwarranted assessments would be attributable to a mixture of causes, only some of which are no fault or choice of theirs. For this reason warranted probabilities would often be used, but in mitigated fashion. Where gamblers arrive at unfavourable outcomes on account of unwarranted assessments which are partially culpable (for example, they did not bother to do some simple sums) and partially non-culpable (for example, they were brought up not to value mathematics), they would receive some level of indemnity short of the full indemnity they would have received had their poor judgment been wholly through no fault or choice of their own. IV. Scarcity The suggestion so far is that, excepting cases of non-culpable incapacity, gamblers are due the warranted expected value of their gambles. This now needs modification to account for an extreme variant of the earlier observation that gambles as a whole might turn out badly. There may simply not be the resources available to deliver the expected value of gambles (or, in cases of non-culpable incapacity, to deliver the outcome expected had no choice been made). Furthermore, this issue of scarcity is not resolved by my proposal that luck is corrected not just among gamblers but among the population as a whole. While it may be the case that the community is a net recipient of good brute luck, it could equally well have net bad brute luck, be brute luck-neutral, or have good brute luck, but not to the same extent as gamblers have bad option luck. In any of these 17 scenarios there will, again, not be the resources to secure the expected value of gambles, and that of non-gambles. So we need some rule to deal with cases where warranted expectations outstrip society’s means. To address this issue we must bear in mind that, from any luck egalitarian perspective, injustice does not issue from individuals being unlucky in an absolute sense – from getting lower total levels of advantage than they would have if fortune did not intervene. Rather, injustice issues from individuals being unlucky in a comparative sense – from getting lower levels of advantage relative to others than they would have if fortune did not intervene. Once this is grasped, handling cases where social resources cannot match gamblers’ expectations becomes much easier, as our goal is then not the impossible one of handing out resources which do not exist, but rather that of adjusting individual advantage levels so that the burden of the overall shortfall is shared fairly. Specifically, I propose that, in cases of scarcity, each individual’s entitlement is reduced by the same percentage as the overall shortfall. Consider a society with two gamblers and one non-gambler, where the gamblers expect, with warrant, 100 units of advantage, but owing to unknown (and unknowable) unfavourable circumstances the winner receives 150 and the loser 20, and the non-gambler is unaffected by luck of any kind and receives 100. The overall amount of advantage in society is 270, which is 30 units, or 10 per cent, less than the expected amount. My proposal is that the fairest result is for each individual to receive 90 units of advantage, so that each individual, including the non-gambler, shares equally in the unexpected gambling shortfall. The gamblers as a group cannot fairly complain about this outcome as, though they have received a level of compensation for their bad luck which does not fully 18 compensate for their loss in absolute terms, their bad luck relative to the non-gambler has been eliminated. The non-gambler cannot fairly complain about this outcome as, though she has been disadvantaged by other people’s gambles, they have, absent compensation, been victims of bad luck relative to her. Had the non-gambler been the victim of bad brute luck, it would be her shortfall that was spread across the community. Without compensation for shortfalls, both gamblers and non-gamblers would be worse off than others, and through no fault or choice of their own. It seems appropriate for surpluses to be pooled in the same fashion as shortfalls, again minimizing unchosen disadvantages. I will now sum up the position outlined above. All-luck egalitarianism is best approximated by a view that undoes the effects of luck not just among gamblers but among the entire community in order to minimize the distributive influence of both option and brute luck. Subject to a proviso, the view gives individuals entitlements to the expected outcomes of their choices which were warranted except insofar as they are non- culpably incapable of recognizing which expectation is warranted, in which case the initial upshot of the ‘choice’ is overturned. The proviso is that, where the community is unable to deliver the expected outcomes of individuals’ choices that were warranted (or equivalent in cases of non-culpable incapacity), or can deliver more than was expected, the societal shortfall or surplus is shared evenly in percentage terms. The form of all-luck egalitarianism described here makes individuals worse off than others only through their faults or choices to make worse decisions in terms of probabilities to which they have access, not through option luck. V. Externalities 19 Is pooling risks between gamblers and non-gamblers, as I have proposed, fair? Daniel Markovits (2008, 287n51; see also Dworkin 1981, 295) claims that ‘enforced risk- pooling would discriminate against those with a taste for risk by making (at least some) gambles practically impossible, thus reducing the range of choice available to risk takers’. But I do not see that it is problematic for the egalitarian to make gambles impossible, given that their primary effect is to create inequalities, and through the medium of luck, at that. There is, however, a more challenging flipside of the above objection. Just as gamblers can complain that whole-population pooling of option luck prevents them from taking risks, so non-gamblers can complain that it forces risks upon them. As an anonymous referee put it, ‘[t]he objection that will be raised against the author’s proposal to share collective luck with non-gamblers is that the gamblers are then imposing an externality over the rest of the population. More precisely, they impose a risk on others who may not want it’. I say this objection is more challenging as wanting to avoid gambles is not obviously in conflict with securing an equal and luck-neutral outcome in the way that wanting to gamble is. I accept that my position implies that gamblers as a group may impose externalities of a sort on the non-gambling group, and that this may seem counterintuitive. But note that these externalities are not typically negative externalities. Rather, the net effect of the externalities on non-gamblers can be expected to be neutral. Where payoffs fall short of expectations, risk-takers do indeed impose negative externalities on non-risk-takers, but where payoffs exceed expectations, the externalities the risk-takers ‘impose’ on non-risk-takers are positive (a transfer of benefits from 20 gamblers to non-gamblers would be forthcoming). Antecedently, there is no reason to assume that negative externalities are more common than positive externalities. This is because, where it is appropriate to respond to expectations, the relevant sort of probabilities are those which are warranted. Thus, even if gamblers tended to be optimistic about their gambles, and so their payoffs failed to match subjective expectations more often than they exceeded them, my form of all-luck egalitarianism would not on that score recommend a net transfer from non-gamblers to gamblers. This shows that the kind of externalities we are talking about are not the net negative externalities found in well-known cases of market failure, such as dangerous anthropogenic climate change. Nevertheless, the non-gamblers’ complaint may still be thought to have some force. Even if they do not expect gamblers’ externalities to make them worse off, they can still complain that they are being subjected to risks that they do not want. Suppose, for instance, that they are very risk averse. In that case, it seems that they are having others’ preferences for risk imposed on them against their will. My position is that this risk imposition is a price worth paying. In some salient cases, at least, the literature seems implicitly to agree. Consider a population consisting of Risk-Taker and Non-Risk-Taker. Suppose Risk-Taker exceeds the speed limit, and crashes, suffering a severe injury. The standard ‘abandonment of negligent victims’ objection to brute-luck egalitarianism centres on the fact that the view would not require Non-Risk-Taker to assist Risk-Taker, as the latter’s bad outcome is a matter of option luck (Fleurbaey 1995; Anderson 1999; Scheffler 2003). But it seems clear that Risk- Taker’s outcome is much worse than what she would have been warranted to expect (most times a driver speeds, they do not crash). So according to my version of all-luck 21 egalitarianism, we can require Non-Risk-Taker to assist Risk-Taker, on the basis that the latter has been unlucky in the sense of receiving less than she was warranted to expect. And this is precisely because egalitarianism construed in this way allows Risk-Taker to impose externalities, such as the cost of Risk-Taker’s medical treatment, on Non-Risk- Taker. Most writers who consider such cases agree that these externalities are appropriate, albeit on non-luck egalitarian grounds (for instance, on account of equal social status requiring that no one’s basic needs be imperiled). This suggests that it is an advantage, not a disadvantage, of my account that it is willing to impose risks on non- risk-takers on the basis of relieving risk-takers of unexpectedly bad outcomes. Furthermore, as this basis is a construal of luck neutralization, the all-luck egalitarian response to the abandonment objection is specifically a luck egalitarian response, not the more typical external imposition on the view. It may be replied that, while externalities are justified in abandonment cases, that is only on account of the dire straits faced by Risk-Taker. Where a different risk-taker is just made a little worse off on account of unexpectedly bad outcomes, no assistance at non-risk-takers’ expense would be justified. Such a response does, however, effectively concede that luck egalitarianism can not itself adequately account for abandonment cases, and must be tempered with some other (perhaps sufficientarian) view in order to deliver the assistance Risk-Taker needs (see Casal 2007, 321-23; Voigt 2007, 404-5).17 That 17 An alternative is to reinterpret luck egalitarianism as not objecting to brute-luck inequalities, in which case providing for basic needs unconditionally might not conflict with luck egalitarianism (see Segall 2010; 2012). This is, however, at odds with luck egalitarian’s distinctive opposition to the differential distributive effects of brute luck, and problematic in other ways; see Knight 2011. Moreover, even if we allow this 22 concession is, I think, out of proportion to the concerns about externalities and risk that motivate it. If we are luck egalitarians, why would we think that imposing non-negative externalities on some, for the sake of preventing luck elsewhere, was such a high cost that we should avoid it even at the cost of giving up our view in the abandonment cases that have been central to the debate? There are relatives of the abandonment cases in which all-luck egalitarianism will offer much less assistance to those disadvantaged through their own actions. Where option luck is barely involved – where the result follows almost directly from choice – little assistance would be forthcoming. This is, I think, plausible, as is suggested by the critics of luck egalitarianism’s focus on the negligent victims of option luck, who face unusually bad consequences of ‘illegal turn[s]’ and ‘slightest mistake[s]’ (Anderson 1999, 295; Fleurbaey 1995, 40). Their arguments would be much less appealing were the ‘victims’ engaged in activities for which a severe injury is a common outcome, such as driving at a tree at high speed. In these cases of ‘predictably destructive victims’, it is doubtful whether we feel that there is an obligation to provide much assistance. But all- luck egalitarianism would still, typically, allow that some assistance (paramedic treatment to prevent death or permanent incapacity, say) is due. Even when one drives at a tree, one might miss, so the expected value is still slightly higher than severe injury. In short, then, all-luck egalitarianism holds that risk-takers may justly impose externalities on non-risk-takers insofar as the former are unlucky. As we have seen, this move, it does not yield a luck egalitarian justification for assisting negligent victims. It only removes the conflict between a non-luck egalitarian justification and luck egalitarianism. 23 equips all-luck egalitarianism to withstand the most familiar external criticism of luck egalitarianism, to wit, that it is too harsh on those with bad option luck.18 VI. Conclusion I have argued that an all-luck egalitarian distribution should have the following features: (a) option luck is neutralized not just by correcting luck among gamblers, but among the community as a whole, because it would be unfair for gamblers as a group to be disadvantaged relative to non-gamblers by bad option luck; (b) individuals receive the warranted expected results of their gambles, except insofar as individuals blamelessly lacked the ability to ascertain which expectations were warranted; and (c) where societal resources are insufficient to deliver expected results to gamblers, gamblers receive a lesser distributive share which is in proportion to the expected results. This form of all- luck egalitarianism allows risk-takers to impose externalities on non-risk-takers, but this seems beneficial in light of the abandonment objection. Although my focus has been on explaining how all-luck egalitarians should handle option luck, my arguments might have implications for views which are not egalitarian. Pluralistic views which include components concerned with absolute well- being and individual responsibility, such as ‘responsibility-catering prioritarianism’ (Arneson 1999; 2000), could construe the responsibility component as treating option luck in the same way as all-luck egalitarianism.19 The responsibility component is usually 18 Another way of resisting this objection is to hold that individual responsibility for disadvantage decreases over time (see Navin 2011; Tomlin 2013). This view could be combined with all-luck egalitarianism. 19 For other such views see Segall 2010, ch. 8; Temkin 2011; Knight 2009b, ch. 6. 24 conceived of as being concerned with neutralizing the inequality-producing effects of luck, and Arneson (2000; 2011) describes responsibility-catering prioritarianism as luck egalitarian. If the best construal of luck egalitarianism is the above form of all-luck egalitarianism – something I do not claim to have proven – it would seem to follow that the responsibility component of pluralistic views should be concerned with replacing the effects of option luck with the expected value of individual choices (corrected for non- culpable incapacity and for any resource shortfall or excess in the ways described). We can, then, acknowledge the worry that all-luck egalitarianism levels down and otherwise violates non-egalitarian norms of justice by combining it with concern for absolute levels of well-being in a pluralistic view. Acknowledgments Research for this article was supported by the British Academy. An antecedent of the paper was presented at the University of Stirling. I thank the participants on that occasion, and especially Simon Robertson for discussion which influenced the present treatment of probabilities. Shlomi Segall and two anonymous referees also provided very helpful written comments. References Anderson E (1999) What is the point of equality? Ethics 109:287-337 Anderson E (2008) How should egalitarians cope with market risks? Theor Inq Law 9:239-70 Arneson R (1989) Equality and equal opportunity for welfare. Phil Stud 56:77-93 25 Arneson R (1999) Equality of opportunity for welfare defended and recanted. J Polit Philos 7:488-97 Arneson R (2000) Luck egalitarianism and prioritarianism. Ethics 110:339-49 Arneson R (2007) Desert and equality. In Holtug N, Lippert-Rasmussen K (eds) Egalitarianism. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 262-93 Arneson R (2011) Luck egalitarianism – a primer. In Knight C, Stemplowska Z Responsibility and distributive justice. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 24-50 Barry N (2008) Reassessing Luck Egalitarianism. J Polit 70:136-50 Cappelen A, Norheim OF (2005) Responsibility in health care: a liberal egalitarian approach. J Med Ethics 31:476-80 Casal P (2007) Why sufficiency is not enough. Ethics 117:296-326 Cohen GA (1989) On the currency of egalitarian justice. Ethics 99:906-44 Dworkin R (1981) What is equality? Part 2: equality of resources. Philos Public Aff 10: 283-345 Dworkin R (2011) Justice for hedgehogs. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA Fleurbaey M (1995) Equal opportunity or equal social outcome? Econ Philos 11:25-55 Fleurbaey M (2001) Egalitarian opportunities. Law Philos, 20:499-530 Fleurbaey M (2008) Fairness, responsibility, and welfare. Oxford University Press, Oxford Fleurbaey M (2011) Four approaches to equal opportunity. In Knight C, Stemplowska Z (eds) Responsibility and distributive justice. Oxford University Press, Oxford 2011, pp 77-97 Knight C (2009a) Describing equality. Law Philos 28:327-65 26 Knight C (2009b) Luck egalitarianism: equality, responsibility, and justice. Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh Knight C (2011) Inequality, avoidability, and healthcare. Iyyun 60: 72-88 Lippert-Rasmussen K (2001) Egalitarianism, option luck, and responsibility. Ethics 111:548-79 Lippert-Rasmussen K (2005) Hurley on egalitarianism and the luck-neutralizing aim. Polit Philos Econ 4:249-65 Markovits D (2008) Luck egalitarianism and political solidarity. Theor Inq Law 9:271- 308 Navin M (2011) Luck and oppression. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 14:533-47 Robertson S (2011) Epistemic constraints on practical normativity. Synthese 181 suppl 1:81-106 Roemer J (1996) Principles of distributive justice. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA Roemer J (1998) Equality of opportunity. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA Scheffler S (2003) What is egalitarianism? Philos Public Aff 31:5-39 Segall S (2010) Health, luck, and justice. Princeton University Press, Princeton Segall S (2012) Why Egalitarians Should Not Care About Equality. Ethic Theory Moral Prac 15:507-19 Temkin L (2011) Justice, equality, fairness, desert, rights, free will, responsibility, and luck. In Knight C, Stemplowska Z (eds) Responsibility and distributive justice. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 51-76 27 Tomlin P (2013) Choice chance and change: luck egalitarianism over time. Ethic Theory Moral Prac forthcoming Vallentyne P (2002) Brute luck, option luck, and equality of initial opportunities. Ethics 112:529-557 Vallentyne P (2008) Brute luck and responsibility. Polit Philos Econ 7:57-80 Vallentyne P (2011) Responsibility and false beliefs. In Knight C, Stemplowska Z (eds) Responsibility and distributive justice. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 174-86 Voigt K (2007) The harshness objection: is luck egalitarianism too harsh on the victims of option luck? Ethic Theory Moral Prac 10:389-407 work_chzymr5adjbzrb7urdfqxf5zai ---- None work_ck2p6qjxqvgbbpmykdnzsvhusm ---- Sociology and Anthropology 7(7): 313-326, 2019 http://www.hrpub.org DOI: 10.13189/sa.2019.070703 Approach to Integrate Indigenous Dispute Resolution Mechanisms as Restorative Justice in Ethiopian Criminal Justice System Abebe Bahiru Bezabh School of Law, University of Gonder, Ethiopia Copyright©2019 by authors, all rights reserved. Authors agree that this article remains permanently open access under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License 4.0 International License Abstract Ethiopia is one of the countries which have compositions of ethnic groups and indigenous peoples, most of which they have endemic modalities of peacekeeping mechanisms and conflict resolutions practices. These varieties of Indigenous Dispute Resolution Mechanisms (hereafter IDRMs) have been using as peaceful means of disputes resolution processes. In practice, despite lack of legal recognition, informally the communities have been utilizing IDRMs to settle criminal disputes including serious ethnic conflicts. The available substantive and procedural criminal laws of Ethiopia are futile to prescribe rules which may perhaps facilitate the incorporation and better use of IDRMs into the criminal justice system. This research aims to respond question how can formal criminal justice system effectively utilize IDRMs? The researcher applied qualitative research methodology that covered both primary and secondary sources. The finding shows that IDRMs necessitates recognition through integration into the formal criminal justice system based on the restorative approach is a valuable assertion. Finally, the writer suggests the application of dynamic and participatory approach of which could recognize IDRMs as a good option to the communities to resolve disputes by the predictable peaceful solution. Such an approach can limit the challenges of the formal criminal justice system; since, those indigenous resolutions are accessible, effective and efficient, less expensive, less coercive and more respectful options. Keywords Indigenous Dispute Resolution Mechanisms (IDRMs), Restorative Justice, Integration, Criminal Justice System 1. Introduction 1.1. Background of the Study Modern formal criminal justice system flourished with modern state formation during the 14th-17th centuries (Skoll, 2009). In the 18th Century, most European countries were at the stage of socio-economic transformation and industrialization. The Egalitarian and dynamic inception of democracy and right protection were spread over Europe and North America. This age of enlightenment branded with the establishment of new perspectives of political administrations, accommodations of the diverse value of moralities, and new perspectives in understanding crime. Legal development and transformation reflected by adoption and transplantation of legal systems. Skoll (2009) describe the age of enlightenment after the overthrow of autocratic and feudal regimes began to be replaced with structured state institutions that granted the opportunity to organize and frame the modern legal system. The enlightenment philosophers and classical criminologist of the 18th Century had significant contributions to legal renovation. Tuori (2010) depicts the development of modern criminal justice influenced by European civil law that was followed by the codification of codes in different categories, and Anglo-American common law school concerned case law or precedent. Some European countries have absorbed the civil law without any revision of their customary or indigenous system; whereas, legal scholars of Germany critically reviewed their indigenous rules before transplantation of the civil law. Former British colonies were accustomed to adopt a common law legal system. In addition, it was necessary to institute the judicial organ which empowered to interpret and enforce the due process of law. Colonizers’, especially in Africa countries, had demanded ‘system’ which instituted by organs of selected legal practitioners, Judges, Juries and focus groups to 314 Approach to Integrate Indigenous Dispute Resolution Mechanisms as Restorative Justice in Ethiopian Criminal Justice System interpret and analyze the implementation of the laws. These establishment processes were administered and organized by state. Protection of the community from heinous criminals affirmed as the responsibility of the state. In doing so, the legal scholars formulated ‘criminal justice system’. In the criminal justice processes, there are two basic models due process model and crime control model (Packer H, 1964). The difference between these two models is, the former characterized to safeguard the protection of the accused; whereas, the latter ambitious to the protection of the public interest. Besides, there are also two criminal justice procedural systems i.e. adversarial and inquisitorial. Adversarial system the parties to conflict act independently and they are responsible for uncovering and presenting evidence in front of a passive and neutral trial jury; the inquisitorial system is different which is the ultimate responsibility for finding the truth is the burden of officials of the justice system. Tuoris (2010) explains that the era of transplantation of legal system, the criminal justice system was inherently adopted by the transformative developing countries, while, they are at the stage infancy to hold perfection of the system. The immediate political benefit of the criminal justice system is ‘social control’ which grants opportunities for the state to administer the community with a monopoly of power (Grace Jennifer, 2004). The excited perception and expectation of states had favored the spread of the criminal justice system to post-colonial Asian and African countries. The criminological origin of conceiving crime and criminals as evil and punishing through punitive methods passed different ‘classical’ and ‘neo-classical’ theories and philosophical formulation stages (Mark & Henry, 2004). Scholars had been pursuing scholarly approaches to contextualize peace, justice, stability, and prosperity. Despite such tremendous efforts, still there is an increasing number of the prison population, increasing criminal recidivism, rising crime rates in ‘modern system’, and the corrupt decision of criminal justice system officials are challenges (UN Restorative Justice Handbook, 2006). The Criminal justice system has been presumed as a cure for crime prevention and the pursuit of justice implicit within the framework of the retributive approach. The transplantation of criminal justice had faced challenges in the midst of pluralistic legal traditions in Ethiopia from its inception up until now. There are more than 85 diversified nations, nationalities, and peoples in Ethiopia. Over 60 indigenous dispute solutions are available which emanated from culture, religion, historical practice of the people (Gebre Yntiso, et al, 2010). To mention few IDRMs; _ Oromo Geda System _ which is practiced in Oromiya Region; Erik ena Shemeglena _ exercised in Amhara Region; Mada _ applied in the border between Afar and Tigray Regions; and etc. The Ethiopian legal tradition is pluralistic due to the presence of such heterogeneous cultural dispute resolution mechanisms. For a long period of time, these cultural dispute resolutions mechanisms have been used to reconcile interpersonal disputes and serious tribal conflicts. This research aims to introduce the approach to indigenous dispute resolution mechanisms as restorative justice in the Ethiopian criminal justice system. The enormous commitments of the state on criminal justice have been surfed less concern to indigenous solutions. Despite this, magnificently in some circumstance, indigenous resolutions have been exercised to resolve serious conflicts; even when the criminal justice has failed to do so. If that is so, why the criminal justice system is overlooked to use those customary dispute resolutions properly? Besides, the question of how to properly integrate the indigenous resolution mechanisms to the criminal justice system is the fundamental issues of this research. 1.2. Objectives of the Study This research intended to explore a better method which helps to utilize indigenous dispute resolutions in the criminal justice system of Ethiopia. Therefore the basic objective of this research is to discuss the way how to integrate indigenous dispute resolutions into Ethiopian criminal justice system in order to enhance functional contributions in solving disputes and serving justice, peace, and stability the community. There are also specific objectives of the main objective:-  To examine the relevance of the application of indigenous dispute resolutions; that could reduce the challenges of the criminal justice system;  To discuss the best approaches to draw lesson to use IDRMs;  To review selected theories of restorative justice which could facilitate to use IDRM; and  To make recommendations for accessible inclusive, collaborative, and participatory criminal justice processes that can integrate indigenous conflict resolution mechanisms. 1.3. Research Questions 1.3.1. General Question  How can we effectively utilize indigenous dispute resolution processes in the Ethiopian criminal justice system? 1.3.2. Specific Questions  What problems hinder to adopt indigenous resolutions?  Is it possible to integrate indigenous dispute resolution into the formal criminal justice system of Ethiopia?  Which approaches or theories do we need to incorporate indigenous dispute resolutions or what Sociology and Anthropology 7(7): 313-326, 2019 315 type of legal and practical formulation is better to integration?  Who is responsible for the proper integration of IDRM? 1.4. Methodology of the Study This is qualitative research that relies on extensive use of primary and secondary sources. The qualitative approach is considered necessary because: first, this research has the objective of exploring or to get an insight about the way of integration of indigenous resolution into the criminal justice process. This research has also objectives that explore the interest of the community and criminal justice system about the usage of cultural dispute resolution in criminal matters. The qualitative approach includes different modes of data collections these are: i.e. primary data collected by structured and semi-structured interview, informal discussion, focus group discussion, and observation. Secondary sources also applied references research findings, books, articles and review of court real cases. 1.4.1. Research Population The study population selected from the officials of the criminal justice system and from the community members who have experience and knowledge about IDRMs. The primary organ of the criminal justice system is the legislative body. Therefore, the researcher conducted an interview with a few Regional Administrative Council members. The legal officers in different levels of criminal procedure including Investigation Police Officers, Public Prosecutors, and Judges are the relevant research population of the study. The samples of this study are collected from Amhara Regional state, one of the regions in Ethiopia which have compositions of IDRMs. The researcher purposefully selected three Zones from the region i.e. South Wollo Zone, North Shewa Zone, and South Gonder Zone. From each Zone, one Woreda (district) has selected which comprise different levels of the criminal justice process and institutional organs. Therefore, generally, three districts have chosen as the target area. The justice system officials including; Judges (district Courts, High Court, and Supreme Court and Regional Cassation court), Public prosecutors and investigation police officers are target population of the study. The other focus group populations are the victims, suspects, offenders and community participants who are using indigenous resolutions as a mechanism to solve the criminal dispute are also basic participant contributors for the research. 1.4.2. Sampling Methods and Size To select the specific target individuals for a qualitative approach, the writer operates a purposeful or judgmental sampling method. Officials of criminal justice institutions have selected by judgmental quota sampling; because, the numbers of cases which are executed by indigenous resolution significantly vary at each level of courts and prosecutor offices. It is obvious Woreda courts (district courts) and prosecutor offices are comparatively entertain enormous criminal cases than any other levels of courts. The sample sizes of the selected population have assigned by the proportional number of professionals in each level of courts from three zones i.e. South Wollo, North Shewa, and South Gonder. From each specific Zone, one district/woreda/ has selected to conduct an interview, group discussion, and observation of indigenous resolution processes. With regard to legislative organ, two regional representatives of the Administrative Council interviewed. While it was difficult to fix the sample size of victims and suspects who exercised the indigenous dispute resolutions; the researcher has used other supplementary methods of focus group discussion with community participants. 1.4.3. Data Collection Tools There are different tools for primary data collections from which this research applied interview, observation, and focus group discussion. In this regard, the interview questions and focus group discussions vary according to the personal contribution and involvement into the criminal justice system or into IDRMs. For instance; the questions which are raised for legislative members have more concerned about the legal status of the region on IDRMs to recognizing the law. Generally, the types and contents of the questions prepared by assessing the responsibilities, positions and expected knowledge on the matter at hand. 2. Introduction to Indigenous Dispute Resolution Mechanisms as Restorative Justice 2.1. Indigenous Resolutions Mechanisms: General Overview Ethiopia is one of the countries which composition of ethnic diversity and endemic customs of conflict resolutions practices. Customary laws have been used for a long period of time that has a tremendous contribution to solving disputes and conflicts which grant sustained peaceful relation of the community. Particularly in the Ethiopian rural areas, the customary process of dispute resolutions has a valuable contribution to settle disputes and to maintain the socio-economical peaceful relations. Before the introduction of theoretical analysis, it is valuable to introduce the concept of what is ‘indigenous’? What makes related to dispute resolution? In fact, the term ‘indigenous’ has used in different perspectives; whereas, this introduction focus is on the concept and relation with the dispute resolution. Most of the cases the word ‘indigenous’ sited in circumstance referred as an indication of ‘distinct identity of something’ for example ‘indigenous 316 Approach to Integrate Indigenous Dispute Resolution Mechanisms as Restorative Justice in Ethiopian Criminal Justice System people’, ‘indigenous language’, ‘indigenous laws’, and etc (Malan Jannie, 2005). While the concept is ambiguous, the word indigenous laterally understand ‘not coming from another place’ or ‘survival of native communities based on cultural, political, and economic realities’ (Burkhardt & George, 2009). There are other complementary terminologies that applied interchangeable words like ‘native’, ‘customary’, and ‘aboriginal’ etc are familiar by different scholars (Damren, 2002). As Proulx Craig (2005) explains indigenous indignity was a redundantly rehearsed to explain circumstances which related with preservation of endemic identities of society before colonization. Most of the post-colonized countries suffered the extinction of native identities. This could be caused by the perception of colonizers to undermine native languages and aboriginal cultural practice as barbaric and primitive. Repealing indigenous customary laws is one of dimension which European colonizers altered indignity of colonies; instead, they brought experiences of their own legal system. For example British colonies faced to serious disaster to sustain their indigenous customary laws which forced to follow Anglo-American common law legal system; similarly, German and French colonies preserved civil law into their legal system. In this regard, Ethiopia is a historic and heroic nation that preserves her from the horrific effect of European colonization. Despite this, the political ambition and dream to create modern Ethiopia cost the nation to neglect the aboriginal resolutions processes by transplanting western laws (Beckstrom, 1973). What is Indigenous Dispute Resolution (IDR)? One reflection of indignity is dispute resolution practice which is performed by aboriginal communities to restore peace according to customary laws (McAuliffe, 2013). Such dispute resolution experiences have special affiliations with culture and religion which conflicts resolved by the participation of the community. Such a community-based approach to crime deeds has accustomed as the essence of integrity for indigenous society. It is not only punishment of the offender rather it is more about restitution of the victim and back the offender to the community. In 2007 the UN has acknowledged the right of indigenous people by Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous People for protection and to the preservation of custom and local identity. Despite the non-binding effect, the declaration has conferred provisions that assert the normative rights and protection of indigenous peoples. Protection of indigenous laws and institutions covered under Article 34 is; Indigenous peoples have the right to promote, develop and maintain their institutional structures and their distinctive customs, spirituality, traditions, procedures, practices and, in the cases where they exist, juridical systems or customs, in accordance with international human rights standards (UN declaration No.61/295). Why Indigenous? There are other phrases which interchangeably used by substituting this conception of cultural dispute resolution. Scholars have been frequently used the phrase ‘Alternative Dispute Resolution’ (ADR) to refer IDRMs in their writings. Their justification is the term ADR includes all types of resolutions which are ‘alternatives’ to the criminal justice system. Of course, in some countries, these cultural dispute resolutions are ‘real’ alternatives and they have impressive roles in assisting the criminal justice system. Whereas, the experience in Ethiopia shows that, despite availability indigenous resolutions have failed to be recognized as ‘real alternatives’. The term alternative dispute resolution is inappropriate to IDRMs because little or no effort has been done to adopt by the criminal justice system. It is unfair to argue those customary solutions are functional alternatives. The community members have devoted to exercise IDRMs without recognition of the state justice organs. There are countries which have experienced with the utilization of indigenous resolution as an alternative to criminal justice with some sort of modification of cultural practice into restorative programs. But, the situation in Ethiopia is unenthusiastic to native solutions. Despite rich compositions of indigenous resolutions, the Ethiopian justice system and native solution experiences still stand in different directions; but both admit one’s importance of the other. The basic question is how can mitigate the theoretical and practical gaps of the two sides. The compromise of such diverse reality would significantly valuable to both; criminal justice system could be assisted by the community participation in the investigation of crime deeds, decision making a role that supposed bring long-lasting crime prevention and decrease crime recidivism; in response native traditional resolutions could improve its performance by the recognition of the criminal justice system. 2.2. The Link between Restorative Justice and Indigenous Dispute Resolution There are tremendous commentary books, research findings, reports published to define restorative justice. It has to confound to be presented in academics as “New paradigm”, “program”, “criminal justice model”, “alternative to dispute resolution” and “community justice”(Daly & Immarigeon, 1998). The origin and concept have not yet settled and seems such contentions continuous. Howard Zehr (2003) who is referred as the grandfather of restorative justice suggested that the motive of restorative justice was started in the 1970s and its effect flourished in 1990s in Canadian Christians and in some European countries. Van Ness and Strong, K. (2009), have sighted Albert Eglash (1955) as the first person who states the term ‘restorative justice’ in 1955 when he wrote an article to suggest types of criminal justice. Braithwaite (2002), one of the influential theorists of restorative justice, has rejected the assumption of origin of restorative justice Sociology and Anthropology 7(7): 313-326, 2019 317 before his work of “Re-integrative shaming theory and restorative shaming”, in 1989. Others have suggested the philosophical conceptions of restorative justice raised far behind human communal history. Disputes and conflicts are part of social life and cultural resolutions have started to use before the revival of the modern criminal justice system; whereas, as Daly (1998) describes that the past of restorative justice was the worst stage of development. However, as Hadley (2006), argues restorative justice is at a deeply rooted spiritual foundation instituted by moral values of the believers and connected with cultural identity. The links between customary dispute resolutions and conception modern restorative justice have flourished in the late 19th century when the community accustomed to solving its’ problem by indigenous resolution mechanisms. So, it would be improper to reject the attributions of native solution that rejuvenated from religious sources and the cultural hierarchy of society elders. Therefore, one can argue the ancient conception of restorative justice was revived from the native community that aspires the characteristics and values of restorative justice. Braithwaite is the one who acknowledged the indigenous societies could be sources of a new vision in serving justice. He appreciates the indigenous traditions of Maori people family based resolution converted to Family Group Conference (FGC) and South African Ubuntu laterally means “I am what I am because of what we all are” or “being-with-others” or “humanity or affection each other” by his recent work ‘Restorative Justice and Responsive regulation’ (Braithwaite (2002). He claims, despite lack of perfection and mismanagement in indigenous tradition, it would contribute to a new vision of justice. The term restorative justice has regarded as controversial based on social, economic and ideological differences between scholars perspectives. Some are elucidated as the third alternative of criminal justice adding with traditional retributive and rehabilitation in the criminal justice system (Zehr (2005). Criminal justice has little room for victims, offenders, and community participation due to a misleading perception of crime is wrong against the state; but in the case of restorative justice, crime presumed wrong against the community. There were attempts to accommodate common definition by Van Ness, Zehr and Marshal T, who are prominent and influential restorative justice scholars. Van Ness and Strong, K. defines; Restorative justice is a theory of justice that emphasizes repairing the harm caused or revealed by criminal behavior. It is best accomplished through cooperative processes that include all stakeholders (Van Ness and Strong, K. (2009). Zehr also define; Restorative justice is a process to involve, to the extent possible, those who have a stake in a specific offense to collectively identify and address harms, needs and obligations in order to heal and put things as right as possible (Zehr, 2003). As Braithwaite, McCold, and Zehr inferred that, ‘the most acceptable working definition’ was offered by Tony Marshall: Restorative justice is a process whereby all the parties with a stake in a particular offense come together to resolve collectively how to deal with the aftermath of the offense and its implications for the future (Braithwaite (2002). The definition consensus is not overwhelming. The contemporary ideal “merging” between community justice and Restorative justice has termed as the greatest challenge to future restorative justice paradigm (McCold, 2004). Scholars admitted external similarities of these two. While, they are also critical about the considerable inner differences; the restorative justice fused to gross collaborative participation of the community with the slight link with criminal justice organs; community justice devoted on action strategies of the criminal justice system (Presser, 2004). In some countries, Youth Offender Prevention Programs and Community Policing and different rehabilitation centers are established proposition and supervision of the criminal justice system. McCold (2004) criticized such experiences which diluted the values of restorative justice. In this regard, there is a paradox as Wheeldon (2009) contested ‘impossible structure of restorative justice’ when if the government is attempting to control processes that shadowed its functionality. Wheeldon furiously criticizes ‘mediation’ will be another sate mode of controlling the society when if it merged with the criminal justice system. There are writers that argued the merger of the two concepts could disrupt the primary vision of restorative justice. But, others strongly denied such critics by confirming these two are not supposed to be controversial rather supportive one to the other. One should not draw hypothetical ‘bridge’ or ‘boundary’ the choice will be the feasibility of restorative justice as a paradigm and the impact on the justice system to restore justice (Presser (2004). In this regard indigenous dispute resolutions are not perfect there are some traditions which could discredit the shinning contributions. Circumstances like disregarding human right principles, ignoring women involvement, prevention of outsiders of the given clan, and some other traditions which could influence the overall quality of participation needed follow-up and supervision by established organ. But, it is shall not mean indigenous resolution should interrupt its substantive values by the state. 2.3. Restorative Justice in Ethiopia and Indigenous Dispute Resolution Mechanisms Are there any conceptions of restorative justice in Ethiopia? In Ethiopia, the concept and origin of restorative justice are not well researched and rare to find the sources in the field. Macfarlane J. by her workshop reflection, ‘Working towards Restorative Justice in Ethiopia: 318 Approach to Integrate Indigenous Dispute Resolution Mechanisms as Restorative Justice in Ethiopian Criminal Justice System Integrating Traditional Conflict Resolution Systems with the Formal Legal System’ described restorative justice as an informal system, as which dominantly practiced in a different part of Ethiopia (Macfarlane, 2007). Her writing is not alleged as research; it is a mere workshop report and personal argumentation on the situation of ‘restorative justice’ and formal justice system. She was not taking time to elucidate what is restorative justice in Ethiopian perspective. She rushed to discussions of the availability of massive religious, tribal informal means or resolutions. Is that possible to argue the Ethiopian indigenous mechanisms identical with restorative justice? There is a lack of critical study in the field; there are of course researches which conducted focus on anthropological discussion of indigenous resolutions processes. Most of the research findings confirmed significant of the customary dispute resolution mechanisms. In recent phenomena, there are attempts to collect the researches by Ethiopian Arbitration and Conciliation Centre (GebreYantiso, 2011). In most of the writings the term “Alternative Dispute Resolution (ADR)” has used interchangeably used to describe traditional resolutions methods. But the question is; does the term is appropriate? Even, Ethiopian Criminal Justice Policy has used the term ADR explicitly to name IDRMs. Whereas the term may not functional name for IDRMs. The reason is; those traditions were not practical alternatives as indicated by the name. That is why this research choose the term ‘indigenous’ to identify those native cultural dispute resolution which the criminal justice system is persistently disregarded to recognize them. To be alternative there have to equal footing and opportunities; unless making two things as an alternative would amount disregarding the disadvantaged. In addition, the term ‘Alternative’ has dispersed argumentations; some said, alternative indicate a choice of the criminal justice system to apply such process that submerges resolution as subsidiary to the formal justice system. The FDRE constitution Article 34 has granted some protection to customary courts for interpersonal disputes and family matters; while, it silent to include criminal cases. Therefore, some have argued the constitution is vague at this context to grant recognition of traditional process to apply on the criminal matters (Ayalew Getachew, 2012). Despite all these controversies, the Ethiopian criminal justice system is dominantly surrounded under consistently practiced endemic cultural resolutions. Before the coming of unfamiliar foreign laws, the societies settled the conflict by religious and tribal informal rules. Historically, the Ethiopian legal system is transplanted from foreign laws that used sources of different basic codes and state made proclamations (Aberra Jembere, 2000). These transplanted European laws were unfamiliar to people and in every stage of codifications, it lacks to concern about indigenous rules. Ethiopian laws/codes have resisted by society due to newness of the legal contents and discriminatory nature of laws by religion, race, ethnic, and sex. Fisher. Z (1971) in his criminal procedure commentary book clearly shows his amazement on action and devotion of Ethiopian government and he criticized futile perception of the prior existences of customary dispute resolutions. Even in present days the Ethiopian criminal justice system is still out of revelation and ignored IDRMs ideally and practically. Little acknowledgment has made in the FDRE Constitution and recent Federal Criminal Justice Policy (2010); whereas, it lacks clarity, specificity, feasibility, and practicability of the rules about the application of IDRMs. Those rules under the policy are not clear whether ADR included indigenous resolutions or not. In addition, the policy is failed to be supported by other specific proclamations or regulations. Consequently, indigenous resolutions have practically ignored to apply with the collaboration of the formal criminal justice system. 2.4. Challenges to Integrate Indigenous Dispute Resolutions Mechanisms Why the communities interested to apply indigenous resolutions? Macfarlane argued society may have different grounds which vary according to distinctive types of modalities. Most of the indigenous resolutions accepted as a reflection of identity that demands courage, honor, respect, and faith by the community (Macfarlane, 2007). Defending cultural identity from extinction could also inspire some users to be devoted and some might be tied to fulfill religious duties. Others could also be pressurized by the community or family to preserve indigenous resolution process. There are suggested external factors attached to problems and failure of the criminal justice system. The content of laws and processes has strange character; in fact, some transplanted laws are not still clear even for lawyers. In addition, other political factors like the illegitimate or corrupt government could reflect by the sign of refusal to exercise cultural solutions. Macfarlane (2007), also mention that when the community mistrusts the state and its bureaucracy it would be reflected by marginalizing and intimidating the criminal justice system and that would empower customary resolution practice. She also redundantly told, ‘extreme poverty and hardship’, Africans’ especially Ethiopians stick with informal resolutions due to extreme situation scarcity of needs including food, house, and cloth which developed the social morality of ‘compromise’ rather than ‘justice’. Despite the fabulous ambition to restorative justice, it has challenges like disorganized formation, many dependencies on criminological theory, imperfect analysis of functional mechanisms; distrust of state its political authority over the society. In addition commitment of the government is a basic challenge to integrate indigenous resolutions; diversity and negative side effect are also bottleneck establishing foundations of cultural dispute Sociology and Anthropology 7(7): 313-326, 2019 319 resolution. Though there are conflicting points, the best result would be flourished when IDRMs and criminal justice system support one another rather than disconnect each other. 2.5. Restorative Justice and Theoretical Frameworks to Apply IDRM's As Wheeldon (2009) describes Pavlich’s appraisal, the ‘paradox identity’ of restorative justice hesitated devotion to integration in the traditional criminal justice system. Andrew Ashworth and Von Hirsch (2003) have contests restorative lacks coherent goals and theories which help to implement and they proposed the ‘making amends’ – suggesting restorative justice as a tool of modification of criminal justice. Others like Barton (2000) draw question ‘What is a fair and just response to a wrongful and criminal act, and how can this best is determined?’ In response for a long period of time, the Retributivism _just desert model and Utilitarian’s _Consequentalist model have been the only option (Kellogg, 1977). However, now a day’s such inceptions changed by ‘restorative justice interventions’ (Barton, 2000). There are writers like Zvi D. Gabbay (2005) analyze the retributive criminal justice would not contradict with restorative justice, the retributive theory of ‘just desert proposed by Von Hirsch (1990), has rehabilitative principles. Rehabilitative response to crime which supposed participatory nature amount the characters of restoration that practiced by welfare states (Duff, 2003). UN position on restorative justice reflected as; ‘successful implementation of restorative justice programs requires strategic and innovative initiatives that build on the collaboration of governments, communities, nongovernmental organizations, victims and offenders’(UN RJ Handbook (2006). The question is which theory is better in molding best to practice restorative justice especially indigenous resolutions. Some argues discovery of the single theory of restorative justice would amount fixing the practice of restoration in a specific area; in this regard, there are numerous theories which criticality analyzed in different perspectives of in deploying restoration practices (Andrew Ashworth and Von Hirsch, 2003). Most of the restorative theories are born from criminological theories. Wheeldon (2009), discerns that the integration of restorative conceptions into criminological theories support its advancements such as social disorganization, social learning, and moral development. Labeling theory, re-integrative shaming, peacemaking theories are also other criminological theories. Of course, there are many restorative theoretical formulations with full of critics. For the purpose of this article, it is better to select a theory that supports the implementation of indigenous resolutions. As Braithwaite (2002) proposed a theory of Responsive regulation is best in merging the government responsibility to intervene and a wider consideration of Persuasion (restorative justice). His proposition is a mixture of varieties of theories consideration of their advantages. Indigenous resolutions are characterized by inhabiting diversified behavior which would sometimes impossible to stick in a single theory. In case we might lack to the categorization of certain indigenous resolution into well-known restorative justice models i.e. VOM (Victim Offender Mediation), FGM (Family Group Mediation), or circle (Zehr, 2003). In this regard, some cultural resolutions have composed of unique characters; so theories could be not fitted properly in different perspectives. One reason could be theories have proposed based on restorative justice ‘programs’ which are framed specified characters. In other words, there are scarce theories to consider cultural resolutions. ‘Reintegrative shaming theory’ – is provided as one of the controversial restorative justice theories due to the linkage between ‘shame’ and reintegration (Harris and Maruna (2006). The theory proposed by Braithwaite in 1989, focusing to explain the procedures of restorative justice conferencing methods. Shame is considered a ‘mysterious emotion’. The conception is wide but that should not perceive as humiliation or degradation of the personality of individuals. Rather it is duly informing the criminal about the consequence of his wrong action further to leads him/her repentance. Controversies surrounded the thesis due to the link of internal morality and emotion which could illusive to proof. Braithwaite’s (2002) Reintegrative shaming thesis proposition concerned the advantages of healthy ‘social disapproval’. Condemnation of criminals should be respectful with forgiveness to bring back the offender to the community; while, this was disregarded by criminal justice. On the contrary disintegrative shaming is a high level of stigmatization label criminals as evil and monster status. Reintegrative shaming has values in regarding deterrence of future criminals by threatening offenders’ social relations. Individuals’ relation tied the trend of morality. Imprisonment has accustomed as a way of living inside the prison as a ‘due’ for criminals rather than rehabilitation centers, or prisons have taken as segregation centers and prisoners as extraneous to the society. Such degradation influenced the generation disrespect the punishment and its deterrence principles. Besides, nowadays we are experiencing horrible crimes that disregarded the morality of human essence at the lowest level. For example, no one could be presumed ‘suicidal bombers’ will be deterred by whatever serous punishment- no more punishment than blowing his/her body into pieces. Some argue shaming by sort of forgiveness has had the contribution more than retributive punishment. Incapacitation by segregation or the death penalty is the disintegrative way of punishment. Criminal justice 320 Approach to Integrate Indigenous Dispute Resolution Mechanisms as Restorative Justice in Ethiopian Criminal Justice System processes are called ‘degradation ceremonies by naming different status of wrongdoer’; from the very inception of the suspect, accused, guilt, convict, prisoner and to master status ex-convict. Labeling theory justifies how the criminal justice system predetermines some behaviors as deviant by the decision of the majority of the community (Mark and Stuart, 2004). ‘Responsive regulation theory’ – formulated by Braithwaite, who is the prominent initiator of this theory, informed law enforcers should be responsive to how effectively citizens or corporations are regulating themselves before deciding whether to escalate intervention. He provided ‘Regulatory Pyramid’ which use as an indicator of ‘when to punish and when to persuade’ (Braithwaite, 2002). Braithwaite pyramid classified crimes and criminals for entitlement of persuasion into three categories. These are restorative justice, deterrence, and incapacitation. At the bottom of the pyramid, it is restorative justice which encompasses ‘persuasion’- that stress on dialogue which applied to virtuous or moral capable offenders. But that is not mean punishment never happen in this level; rather it is the matter of priority. At the middle of the pyramid is about little-bit serious criminals that presumed in need of punishment for deterrence purpose and offender is supposed to have ‘rational actor’ who refrain from further wrongdoings. The top of the pyramid is classification about incapacitation (imprisonment and death penalty) which ordered to irrational offender like serious criminals like a psychopathic serial killer. Criminal justice system ‘regulatory formalism’ is criticized as an emphasis on strict prosecution. The responsive theory has suggested these strict formal criminal justice processes need a revision of prior steps before prosecution. Those steps could dialogue, group discussions (before and after crime commission), notice, mediation, and warnings in different forms (written or oral). In short, the theory perceived ‘gives the chance for wrongdoers’ to reconsider his/her character. But that is not mean the criminal is free of punishments each of the three levels. Accordingly, this theory advice to amend the fault of perception of the formal justice system which granted priority of prosecution for every crime and criminals, by indicating that all crimes and criminals should not always be supposed to apply punishment. Punishment presumed the last resort that comes when persuasion is failed. So, by applying this principle as ground, enforcement of indigenous resolutions could be explained. That means the state would permit the interventions of indigenous resolution in strict responsive approach. 2.6. The Experience of other Countries on Indigenous Resolution and Restorative Justice There are countries which actively exercise indigenous resolution in a different form, whether by transforming their own cultural practice into a specialized entity of criminal justice organ or some others adopt other countries experience into their modalities by modifying the customary rules supporting with legal frameworks. In this regard European and Anglo-American countries like that of New Zealand, Australia, and Canada, have excellent experiences. Despite, distorted resistance of some nations, Braithwaite emphatically suggested that, Western nations need to open themselves to learning not only from the restorative practices of their own indigenous peoples but also from Asian, Polynesian, African, and other cultural traditions of restorative justice. There are also the African countries that applied their customary dispute resolution even for serious international crimes, for example, Rwanda ‘Gachacha’ and Truth and Reconciliation in South Africa are the most outspoken experiences. Technically, these countries have been acquired enormous advantages from indigenous resolution. Accordingly, most of the Anglo-American countries adopted restorative justice in different approaches and distinct anomalies. Some of are: ‘Alternative to Prosecution’, ‘Diversion’, ‘Differed’, and ‘Alternative to imprisonment are examples’. Some states also asserted various institutional programs dependent or independent to the criminal justice system including Juvenile and Youth Delinquency correctional programs and rehabilitation centers. These methods aim at diverting the suspect out of the criminal justice system at the earliest possible stage or after conviction (Peter Talk, 2005). 3. Integration of IDRM with the Criminal Justice System The data collected from the study area community participants shows that the demand to use customary dispute resolution mechanisms is very high. However, most of the informants criticized the criminal justice system which is legally and practically reluctant to endorse IDRMs. Basically, the informants confirmed the demand to outline use IDRMs its indignity and independence from any inconsistent foreign intervention. One of the member of Aweramba community told that, the victim of crime who reports a case to the criminal justice system has to patiently wait for long processes of investigation, prosecution, court adjudication, and final judgment. The number of criminal cases adjudicated in the formal justice system is the smallest in proportion to the total number of criminal disputes in the community. The study informants concerned that, the cases brought to criminal justice system encountered with serious procedural delay, the mistake of fact, false accusation, false witnesses, the corrupt practice of criminal justice officials’, and wrongful conviction. These problems have caused the community to be uncertain on the criminal justice system, and highly interested to use those customary dispute Sociology and Anthropology 7(7): 313-326, 2019 321 resolution methods. For example interview with Zumera who is founder and father of the Aweramba Community, shows that justice shall be served by considering the indigenous solutions. According to Zumera, the social structure of Aweramba community is peaceful and dignified. Some interview respondent has also proved Aweramba community is relatively crime free society. The community has a self-administered justice process by the indigenous resolution. Police have little experience to solve ‘private compliant’ criminal matters by ADR mechanisms. Despite lack of proper formal and legal support, as some investigation police officers attest to that, they have been informally resolving criminal cases, even serious conflicts by IDRM. Despite, such inconsistent practice the police firmly acknowledged the advantage and positive contribution to the peaceful relationship and stability of the community and prevention of commission of the crime. Legally, Police neither clearly authorized to resolve cases by IDRMs, nor prohibited such discretion. They suggested formalization of the irregular use of IDRMs into a coherent experience by assigning authorized responsible organ. The interviewed informant polices officers suggested that; it would be able to be coherent and fruitful if there is some sort of legal frameworks to specify the responsible organs to supervise of IDRMs. Court Judges and public prosecutors concerned the circumstances of criminal dispute resolution which has been inundated with complicated legal and practical challenges. First, the community including victim preferred practice IDRMs, even for serious public matters. Second, criminal justice has lacuna to organize coherent legal frameworks and responsible organs to accommodate such community interest. Third, there is a lack of legal experts in the field of indigenous laws. The prosecutors argued that there is ‘legal deficiency’ in the field of IDRMs. Ethiopian criminal laws are reluctant to include flexible provision of restorative nature. Prosecutors and Judges admitted the undeniable contribution towards the accessibility and fairness, as well as complementing the efficiency of the justice sectors. To exercise the IDRMs fruitfully the court Judges suggested the enactment of substantive and procedural laws. The research finding shows that it neither demanded free ride of the IDRMs nor strictly controlled by the state. It rather desires the collaboration between the criminal justice system and IDRMs to have a prominent contribution for technical balance and incredible accreditation of each other. The equilibrium would be able to support the balance of interest between the community demands of IDRM values and considerable collaboration with the state. The responsible organs of the state should have the ambition to grant credit for the IDRMs. Since the processes should be collaborative as ‘give and take policy’ the IDRM benefited state protection and promotion via to policy making and other legal frameworks. The criminal justice system also cultivates the advantage from the IDRMs to solve challenges the inefficient and inaccessible criminal justice processes. The justice officials are interested in the applicability of IDRMs. The criminal justice system should enhance the processes based on the enactment of policy and other laws which help the application of IDRM. Unless otherwise, the present dissected practice of IDRM is support by the state a relational function it will be difficult to be fruitful. Comparatively, this approach has wider recognition of the merit of both IDRMs and formal criminal justice system. The communities follow the trend of their customary resolutions and they support by the criminal justice system or any responsible organ sponsored by state or NGOs’. The integration approach is better to be operational through the devotion of the community and collaboration of the criminal justice organs. So, there must be some coherent formal integration policy of IDRMs in regional level which can help to handle the extensive participatory procedure of dispute resolutions. 3.1. Combined Stochastic - Responsive Regulation To integrate the IDRMs the responsive regulation need to have the additional consideration of community interests besides to offenders’ rationality. The criminal justice system should grant an equal probabilistic opportunity to all crimes and criminals to use IDRMs based on the combined assessment of community interest and rationality of the offender. Therefore the researcher suggested applying stochastic approach which is a diverse triangulation of criminal cases in specific localities. Stochastic can be described as a process or system that is connected with random probability, or the state of criminal matters can have the probability to apply the IDRMs’. Here means, there should be no specific lists of crimes or specific criminals, it rather every criminal matter should have a probability of applying IDRMs. There are several IDRMs which have a different approach to crimes and criminals; most of them are related to moral and religious values. Therefore, based on the combined stochastic approach we need to respect not only offenders’ rationality it also the communities’ perception towards the crime. If we are limiting the IDRMs only to select the rational offender, it will disregard the social interest of the community. Accordingly, the states’ national intervention approach via policy or legal perspective should be probabilistic in consideration of the morality and cultural values of the society. For instance, the conflicts between the Amhara and Afar border have been solved through customary resolution. Conflict is prevalent between the pastoral community of Afar and Amhara around regional borders due to the pretext of possession of grazing land. Sometimes the conflict has out of control to the administration of security organs which resulted in the loss 322 Approach to Integrate Indigenous Dispute Resolution Mechanisms as Restorative Justice in Ethiopian Criminal Justice System of human life and destruction of properties. The same is true with other areas for example border between Afar vs Somali; Oromiya vs Somali; Afar vs Somali etc. But, the indigenous resolution has not supported in other specific areas that are different one locality to the other. For example in Aweramba community crimes of homicide between families solved by their indigenous mechanisms whereas, such a solution may not work in somewhere in other parts of the country. So, the criminal justice system shall be flexible in considering the IDRMs based on each community’s interest as far as the solution is a predictable peaceful feature in the society. The IDRMs have a difference from place to place; some apply for serious crimes others selective to simple crimes. Thus, national integration policy of IDRMs as principle shall not be fixed to listed crimes or criminals; since there are significant discrepancies between the values of the community. Whereas, it should be clear that IDRM should not be careless anticipation enthuses. In fact, random indicates the discrepancy of offenses which can solve by IDRMs in collaboration with the community and the criminal justice system. Despite, the lack of formal processes, it is undisputed the contemporary criminal justice system sporadically attempted to utilize IDRMs to every criminal dispute. Therefore, the community deserves to choose the best solution for the dispute and the state shall be flexible to use those IDRMs. The approach of stochastic can granted the recognition of those inconsistent applications of IDRMs. Contemporarily, no matter the crime and criminal behavior the criminal justice system was unsuccessful to stop the community from using IDRMs. As discussed above, there are many examples in the Amhara region; Aweramba in Fogeraworda, ‘Ydem-Erke’ in Lalo-mama meder Woreda and Amare in Wogdiworeda. The interviewed informants in these areas confirmed that the communities considerably using IDRM even for serious crimes like that of homicide and rape. The way of applying is inconsistent and without acknowledgment of the criminal justice system. In Combined – Stochastic Theory- the processes of IDRMs shall have formal recognition by the criminal justice system. In doing so, the criminal justice system shall establish a responsible organ to the supervision of IDRMs. The organ needs to be authorized by the regional justice Bureau and dawn to local justice offices in woreda/district level. This organ shall be independent to facilitate the regional and local utilization of IDRMs. The functions, duties, and responsibilities and composition of this organ shall determine by law. The mode of integration can succeed by the establishments of an organ which suggested connecting the criminal justice system and IDRMs. The organ shall protect the norm and customs of the community – it should promote the cultural practice and recognize the morality of society. In addition, the processes of the election of members of this organ shall be free of any political, social and economic influences of the state. The organ needs to have the mandate to support and appreciate the practice of IDRMs. (a) (b) Figure 1. (a) Formal criminal justise system (Retributive Approach towords IDRMs); (b) Integration of IDRMs’ with Criminal justise system Sociology and Anthropology 7(7): 313-326, 2019 323 In the contemporary processes of retributive criminal justice approach, the formal criminal justice system and IDRMs has disrupted by challenges. (See Figure-(a)) The criminal justice system much focus search of criminal punishment, while the community has determined to apply cultural solutions. The barrier is a lack of collaboration and clear acknowledgment. The regional state of Amhara involved some dispersed approach to use those restorative IDRMs. The police via-to community policing and formal criminal justice investigation process; prosecutors and Woreda/district/ courts used ‘ADR’ for simple private compliant matters to revoke criminal cases. Such dismantled approach is overlapped one to the other sometimes there are also confusions as to whom and how those organs share duties. Besides, those attempts lack efficiency and effectiveness. The criminal justice has still stood in such confusing circumstances neither determined to the effective operation of IDRMs nor totally ignored the IDRMs. Such disconnected processes can be sorted by the reasonable recognition of IDRM through the stochastic approach. The offender and victim have a chance to solve disputes based on their own selection of indigenous resolution mechanisms. There must be responsible organ [(see above figure (b)] to coordinate the overall process of IDRM which collaborates and support with the criminal justice system. The IDRM coordinating organ might support and finance by the NGOs or the government. It expected to avoid negative challenges of IDRMs by awareness creation training and other mechanisms with the collaboration of the regional state Justice Bureau. This organ shall be established at the regional level to solve the problem of the responsible authority to integrate the IDRMs. Accordingly, the IDRMs can resolve cases by the full consent of the victim, offender, and participation of the community. The process shall be supervised by the IDRMs coordinators who should assess the process of resolution is fair and impartial. The decision of the IDRM should be biding which can be referred to criminal justice organs including to police, public prosecutor, or court. Criminal matters could be diverted from the criminal justice system to indigenous dispute resolution processes from any stage of formal criminal justice proceedings. When the matter is failed to be solved by IDRMs the case shall immediately be transferred to the formal criminal justice system. In addition, the criminal justice system should collaborate via awareness creation training about human right protection, fairness and providing security and peace of the community. Such a mode of integration benefits the criminal justice process through the participation of the community in solving problems. 3.2. Process of Integration via Stochastic – Community Interest This approach has propositions for further discussion of the practical analysis; 1. The first proposition is when the community is against the criminal justice system and in support of using IDRM, in principle the criminal justice system should be positive towards the community reaction. But it could be negative in the exceptional case against the choice of the community. The community may choose to apply the cultural solution to solve criminal disputes. Such practice has been neglected by the formal criminal justice system. The criminal justice system should evaluate the interest of the community; whether the dispute is peacefully settled with the active participation of the society or not. Exceptionally, community elders’ decisions might unsuccessful to resolve disputes; in such case, criminal justice should respond by using formal criminal procedure steps. The IDRMs coordinating organ play role to organize the referral of cases from the IDRMs to the formal criminal justice system and the reverse. The criminal justice system needs to develop trust on the community – the assumption of sole justice is delivered from the state should change and the principle of “bottom-up”- justice shall be done by the community. 2. The second proposition is when if the community is a support to use the criminal justice system and against the IDRMs, the criminal justice system should respond positively to accept the case. In some circumstance, there are cases which the community demands the direct intervention of the criminal justice system. IDRMs might unsuccessful or impossible due to the diversified interest of the community or due to other reasons. In such circumstance, the formal criminal justice system needs step-up to entertain the case by formal criminal procedures. That means when if the community dislike the specific criminal matter to be solved by IDRMs, the state shall be responsible to continue the formal proceedings. The IDRMs coordinating organ shall also to transfer cases from IDRMs to criminal justice organs. 3. The third proposition is, when the criminal justice system is against the IDRMs – the community should assume positive in principle towards the criminal justice system, and might exceptionally reject the position of the criminal justice system. Currently, the criminal justice system intervened in the processes of IDRMs based on the reason of protection of peace and security. When the criminal justice system is responsible to the community, the act of intervention supposed to benefit society. Thus, the community has to acknowledge and should work with the criminal justice system. But, in some situation state might interfere due to 324 Approach to Integrate Indigenous Dispute Resolution Mechanisms as Restorative Justice in Ethiopian Criminal Justice System political or administrative interests. Beyond community peace and security; state political affiliated intervention shall be resisted by the society that has been happening in the present situation when the community reflected through boycotting or refusing the intervention of the criminal justice system. Therefore, the state should reassess its involvement is based on the willingness and interest of society. 4. The fourth proposition is when the criminal justice system in support of IDRMs the community should be positive. The positive responses of integration and ongoing desire of ambition of the criminal justice system can be evaluated by cooperation between the IDRMs coordinating personals and the criminal justice system professionals. Supporting and advocating the process of IDRMs through policy enactment and lawmaking will be able to flourish the success. The collaboration should be in a certain scope of limitation, the criminal justice organs have to respect the norms, values, and moralities of the society. In reverse, the indigenous resolution participants in the processes of IDRMs should also assist the criminal justice system. To clarify the proposition by showing a practical example, Aweramba community is one of the established societies in Amhara Region state in South Gonder Fogera Woreda. This community has its own peaceful indigenous resolution processes. Criminal disputes have chance entertained by family-based dispute resolution processes which led by the community elders. Zumera who is father and founder of this community has the role of settling every type of dispute in the area. On the session of focus group discussion with community members all participants reflected they used to apply their cultural dispute resolutions to settle criminal matters. To highlight the propositions; 1. The first proposition is when the community is much favored the IDRMs the justice system has to tolerate the interest of the society. The Aweramba community has a choice to apply the customary dispute resolution then the justice system could cooperate through IDRMs coordinating organ. Therefore regional coordinating organ shall play the role of facilitation and cooperation. 2. The second proposition is when the community is demanded the direct intervention of the formal criminal justice system, the justice system shall use the integration organ to intervene and apply the formal criminal justice processes. In some circumstance, Aweramba community members might request the formal justice system assistance or intervention then in such situation the justice system shall be cooperative to settle matters through formal criminal justice processes. 3. The third proposition is when the formal justice system is interested to intervene in the IDRM processes; such intervention shall be taken positively. But such a proposition is to aim the protection of the society from the negative impact of the IDRMs. For example, when if the decision of the Aweramba community dispute resolution is suspected of negative effect against the public interest of the society the formal criminal justice system shall intervene via coordinating organ. Such intervention shall be independent and free from any political interest of the justice system and it shall be assessed case by case. 4. The fourth proposition is when if the criminal justice system is interested to assist the IDRMs the community shall accept the cooperation. For instance, when the justice system is devoted to supporting Aweramba community indigenous resolution mechanism, it shall be positively interpreted. However such cooperation shall be free of strange intervention to the community. Generally, the stochastic approach can be applied through the collaboration of the formal criminal justice system and the indigenous dispute resolution mechanisms. 4. Conclusions In Ethiopia, almost every criminal matter including serious crimes, have been resolved according to the customary laws and indigenous dispute resolution mechanisms. The indigenous dispute resolutions have a magnificent contribution to solving criminal disputes that can support the criminal justice system in different forms. The formal retributive criminal justice system inundated with continuing challenges that related to victims participation, community interest, and lesser concern to the harms of victims and restoration of the damage. In addition, the criminal justice system has criticized by high cost, delay, ineffectiveness, increasing number of the prison population, and inefficient deterrence effects. Even more, serious problems of crime sin investigation which is more dependent on the oral witnesses have obsessed the legal personals to corrupt and mistaken decisions. So, the main theme of this research is to investigate the way how to utilize IDRM effectively by integrating with the formal justice system. The research finding shows the two, both the formal criminal justice system and IDRM, shall approach each other with the intervention of third ‘organ’. So, the integration processes have to reconsider the essences and benefits of each other. Therefore the researcher has proposed a solution to the integration of IDRMs into the criminal justice system as restorative justice to confer the method which the contemporary criminal justice system to be accessible, participatory, effective and efficient. The integration of IDRM suggested using the stochastic national approach Sociology and Anthropology 7(7): 313-326, 2019 325 which determines by assessments of the interest of both formal criminal justice system and the community participants including victims and offender. Since these two has collaborated the utilization processes will be effective and efficient. 5. Recommendations To utilize IDRM effectively the researcher suggested the following solutions; i. Amendment of Legal Frameworks The Federal laws including the FDRE constitution, criminal justice policy have failed to recognize the IDRMs. Besides, the criminal code and criminal procedure code ignore the very idea of indigenous resolutions. Even the draft criminal procedure is not embraced provision about IDRMs. So, the federal legislative organ shall enact or amend those legal frameworks. Regional states granted by the federal constitution to formulate policy and strategy that states would enact policy about the IDRMs. Regional governments’ initiation and commitment have a considerable contribution to the proper formulation of guideline for the application of IDRMs. So, the regional state shall enact the policy document which offers acknowledgment of integration and formal utilization. Further, the regional state can frame criminal law that recognizes IDRMs which is not covered by the federal criminal law. Hence, the regional council can formulate provision about the integration of IDRMs. ii. Establishment of IDRMs Coordinating Organ The IDRMs require permanent and responsible organ to coordinate the processes. The effects of a lack of responsible organ reflected through multiple confusions of different institutions. The Federal Ministry of Justice shall have specifically designated to coordinate and supervise regional states performance. Structurally the Federal IDRM coordination organ shall be established by law. Besides, the coordination organ must also establish at the regional level. The regional coordination organ shall be responsible for the Regional Justice Bureau and the power and duties must be determined by the law. The IDRMs coordinating organ institute by the collaboration of the criminal justice system which aims responsibility to facilitate and support the IDRMs’. The responsibilities of this organ are to facilitate the processes of integration by providing necessary infrastructures, selection of independent personnel to coordination role, provide training and other coordination roles. As it is the nearest to each cultural dispute resolution the regional coordination organ shall be responsible for the integration of IDRMs. This organ must scrutinize the features and resolution processes of each cultural resolution methods. Further, this organ shall propose an action plan for the implementation of IDRMs. iii. Conduct Research works The regional IDRMs are diversified in type and character which complicated the harmonization processes. To clarify the challenges extensive empirical researches have to be conducted. There are various characteristics of IDRMs; to accommodate and discern such diversified interests the Regional Justice Bureau should conduct research. The studies should also scrutinize the methods of integration of the criminal justice system. iv. Resolve Financial Constraints The state shall be committed to allocate budget to the establishment and integration processes of the IDRMs. Unless financial constraints solved, the researches and proposed means of utilization will be out of a function or fruitless effort. For this purpose, the regional state shall offer a proper amount of budget. There are also the possibilities to find financial support from different NGOs’. v. Legal Experts and Law Schools Other countries experience shows that in their law school curriculum there are courses dedicated to studying the indigenous laws, but there is no such experience in Ethiopia law schools. Ethiopian law schools devoted studies on transplanted foreign laws. Even more, the law schools dedicated the scrutiny of researches that analyze the codified laws. In addition, most of the legal writings drastically been dreaming ‘modern laws’ and subordinate the indigenous laws. Accordingly, legal experts who graduate from higher education knew foreign laws while they don’t know about their own indigenous laws. Due to that, there is a problem of legal experts in the field of IDRMs. Therefore, as recommendation Ethiopian law schools should be fruitful to assess and give due consideration on indigenous laws. REFRENCES Aberra Jembere, (2000). An Introduction to the Legal [1] History of Ethiopia 1434–1974. Hamburg, Germany. Ayalew Getachew Assefa (2012). Customary Laws in [2] Ethiopia: A Need for Better Recognition? A Women’s Rights Perspective. Danish Institute for Human Rights (DIHR). p.24. Barton, C., (2000). Theories of Restorative Justice, Just [3] Peace? Peace Making and Peace Building for the New Millennium.Massey University Centre for Justice and Peace Development. (pp. 63 – 73). Beckstrom John H. (1973). Transplantation of Legal [4] Systems: An Early Report on the reception of Western Laws in Ethiopia. The American Journal of Comparative 326 Approach to Integrate Indigenous Dispute Resolution Mechanisms as Restorative Justice in Ethiopian Criminal Justice System Law. Vol.21. Braithwaite J, (2002). Restorative Justice and Responsive [5] Regulation. Oxford University Printing, p.3 Burkhardt Kate J. & George G. (2009). Restorative [6] Justice.Psychology Crime & Custom. 48-410. Daly K. and Immarigeon R. (1998). The Past, Present, and [7] Future of Restorative Justice: Some Critical Reflections. The contemporary criminal Justice Review, P.2. Damren Samuel (2002). Restorative Justice Prison and the [8] Native Sense of Justice, Journal of Legal Pluralism. No.47. pp.83-111. Duff, A. (2003). Restoration and Retribution, ‘in’ Von [9] Hirsch, A, Roberts, J. V., Bottoms, A. (et al), Competing or Reconcilable Paradigms?. Hart Publishing. Oxford. p.43. Federal Democratic Republic of Ethiopia Constitution, [10] Federal Negarit Gazeta, (1995),Addis Ababa (Ar.34, 39, & 78) Ethiopian Criminal Justice Policy (2010). p.38. [11] Fisher S.Z. (1971). Traditional Criminal Procedure in [12] Ethiopia. HSU, Am. J. Comp. L. Vol. 19, p.709. GebreYntiso, et al (Eds), (2011) Customary Dispute [13] Resolution Mechanisms in Ethiopia. Addis Ababa. Grace Jennifer (2004). The Challenges of the Restorative [14] Justice process in Aboriginal communities through Social Economic and Political Perspectives. MA thesis, Carleton University, Ottawa, Ontario. p.4. Hadley Michael L. (2006). Spiritual foundations of [15] restorative justice, in Sullivan, D. and Tifft, L.(eds). Handbook of RJ a New Perspective. Harris Nathan and Maruna, Shadd (2006). Shame, [16] Shaming, and Restorative Justice: A critical appraisal, ‘in’ Dennis Sullivan and Larry Tifft, (eds). Handbook of RJ A Global Perspective p.452. Johan Griffins (1970). Ideology in criminal procedure or a [17] third “model” of the criminal process. The Yale Law Journal. Kellogg, R.F (1977). From Retribution to “Desert” The [18] Evolution of Criminal Punishment. George Washington University. American Society of Criminology, p.3. Louw Dirk J. (2006). The African Concept of Ubuntu and [19] Restorative Justice, ‘in’ Sullivan, D. and Tifft, L. (eds), Handbook of Restorative Justice: A Global Perspective. p.161. Macfarlane. J.,(2007).Working Towards Restorative Justice [20] in Ethiopia: Integrating Traditional Conflict Resolution Systems with the Formal Legal System. Cardozo J. Vol. 8:487. Malan Jannie, Indigenous Dispute Resolution and [21] Reconciliation: Past, Present, and Future, University of Botswana. p.13. Mark M. Lanier and Stuart. Henry (2004). Essential [22] Criminology, 2nd (eds), Westview, USA. McAuliffe Padraig, (2013). Romanticization Versus [23] Integration? Indigenous Justice in Rule of Law Reconstruction and Transitional Justice Discourse. Goettingen Journal of International Law. pp. 41-86. McCold P. (2004). Paradigm Muddle: The Threat to [24] Restorative Justice Posed by Its Merger with Community Justice. Contemporary Justice ReviewVol. 7, No. 1.pp.13– 35. Murado Abdo (2009). Legal History and Tradition of [25] Teaching Material. Justice. Legal System Research Institute. p.220. Packer H. L (1964). Two models of the criminal process. [26] University of Pennsylvania law Review vol.113. Peter Talk (2005). Method of diversion used by the [27] prosecution service in the Netherland and other Western European countries. 135th International Senior seminar visiting Experts Paper. Resource Material Series. Presser Lois, (2004). Justice Here and Now: A Personal [28] Reflection on the Restorative and Community Justice Paradigms. Contemporary Justice Review Vol. 7 No.1. Taylor & Francis Ltd. pp.101–106. Proulx Craig (2005). Blending Justice: Interlegality and the [29] Incorporation of Aboriginal Justice into the Formal Canadian Justice System. Journal of Legal Pluralism. No.51. pp.79-110. Skoll Geoffrey R.(2009). Contemporary Criminology and [30] Criminal Justice Theory Evaluating Justice Systems in Capitalist Societies. Palgrave Macmillan. New York. Tuori Kaius (2010). Legal Pluralism and Modernization: [31] American Law Professors in Ethiopia and the Downfall of the Restatements of African Customary Law. University of Helsinki Faculty of Law, Legal Studies Research Paper Series. No 3. UN Handbook on Restorative Justice (2006). [32] United Nations Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous [33] Peoples No.61/295 (2007). Resolution adopted by the General Assembly. Published by UN 2008. Van Ness D & Karen Strong (2009). (4thed). H. Restoring [34] Justice: An Introduction to Restorative Justice. Von Hirsch A. (1990). The politics of “Just deserts”. School [35] of Criminal Justice. Rutgers University. New Jersey. Von Hirsch A, Ashworth, et al (2003). Specifying Aims and [36] Limits for Restorative Justice; A making amends ‘Model?. Hart Publishing. Oxford and Portland. p.21. Wheeldon, J., (2009). Finding common ground: restorative [37] justice and its theoretical construction(s,) George Mason University. Fairfax, Virginia, Contemporary Justice Review Vol. 12. No. 1, 91–100. Zehr, H, (2003). Little Book of Restorative Justice, [38] Pennsylvania. Good Books. p. 4. Zehr, H. (2005). (3rded). Changing Lenses: a new focus for [39] criminal justice. Scottsdale PA: Herald Press). p.177. Zvi D. Gabbay (2005). Justifying Restorative Justice: A [40] Theoretical Justification for the Use of Restorative Justice Practices. Journal of Dispute Resolution. Vol.2, p.349. 1. Introduction 2. Introduction to Indigenous Dispute Resolution Mechanisms as Restorative Justice 3. Integration of IDRM with the Criminal Justice System 4. Conclusions 5. Recommendations REFRENCES work_cklo7af33zg6ngmaswthnh5n2u ---- This is the post-print of Archer, A. 2014. Designing multimodal classrooms for social justice. Classroom Discourse. 5(1): 106-116. DOI: 10.1080/19463014.2013.859842. It is made available according to the terms of agreement between the author and the journal, and in accordance with UCT’s open access policy available: http://www.openuct.uct.ac.za/sites/default/files/UCTOpenAccessPolicy.pdf, for the purposes of research, teaching and private study. E-mail: Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za 1 Designing multimodal classrooms for social justice Arlene Archer Writing Centre, Centre for Higher Education Development, University of Cape Town Abstract This paper explores the ways in which multimodal classroom discourse could inform a social justice agenda through broadening the base for representation in the classroom. It identifies some of the challenges and opportunities of designing multimodal classrooms in diverse and developing contexts, where there are vast differentials in terms of access to resources. It focuses on the ways in which multimodal classrooms could recognize a range of student resources, whilst at the same time enabling access to dominant forms. This includes access to the discourses and knowledges of official curricula, and formal methods of assessment, as well as the creation of dispositions towards meaning-making outside of the classroom. Formal education often closes down access to a range of semiotic resources and multimodal classrooms can potentially recover ‘recognition’ of these. This paper explores ways of designing multimodal classrooms for social justice in order to surface the range of students’ resources which are often not noticed or valued in formal educational settings. It proposes the following: the questioning of boundaries between domains, harnessing students’ representational resources, developing metalanguages for reflection, and creating less regulated classroom spaces. Key words Multimodality, access, recognition, social justice mailto:Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za E-mail: Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za 2 Introduction This paper explores ways of designing multimodal classrooms for social justice, looking at examples from some South African classrooms. It showcases interventions in a range of disciplinary domains, including Pharmacology, Communication Studies, Civil Engineering, and English. The challenge is to facilitate recognition of students’ diverse resources, whilst at the same time enabling access to the content and discourses of official curricula and formal methods of assessment. Multimodal classrooms go beyond written and spoken language to overtly encourage classroom tasks that require multiple forms of representation, such as writing, image, speech, gesture and music. This paper argues that broader conceptions of semiotic resources and ways of communicating could allow for reconceptualising which textual practices count and for whom, thus highlighting relations of power, inequality and social boundaries. In South Africa, teachers and theorists drawing on multimodal approaches have tended to interrogate power differentials and social justice (Archer 2006; Harrop-Allin 2011; Newfield 2011; Stein 2008; Stein and Newfield 2006; Thesen 2001, 2007). Resources like local languages and indigenous knowledge practices were undervalued under the previous political regime, and many teachers and researchers have attempted to recognize a range of students’ resources which are often not valued in formal classroom settings, including cultural forms and knowledges. In educational contexts in South Africa there is still differential access to education and to resources such as textbooks, computers, teachers. The medium of instruction remains predominantly English. However, students have multiple language systems to draw on, and there is often a degree of fluidity and movement between languages and language varieties. In order to recognize the resources that marginalized South Africans have developed, it is necessary to focus on student agency in textual design. Recognition, agency and choice An approach that takes into account the full range of semiotic resources has the potential to make classrooms more democratic and inclusive. Such an approach could enable marginalized students’ histories, identities, languages and discourses to emerge through “broadening the base for representation” (Stein and Newfield 2006: 9). ‘Recognition’ of resources is an important feature of designing multimodal classrooms for social justice. ‘Recognition’ is about noticing resources in terms of some existing framework and integrating these in a range of contexts. The use of modes in classrooms is always “the effect of the work of culture, history and power in shaping materials into resources for meaning- mailto:Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za E-mail: Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za 3 making” (Stein 2008, 122). So, recognition of resources also entails recognition of how power is operating in varying social practices. By resources, I mean both students’ resources, as well as semiotic resources, such as colour. People choose how to represent meaning from a range of possible options which are crucially shaped within a particular context. This may mean drawing on resources that were previously devalued and marginalized to the extent that they were deemed inappropriate in an educational setting. The meaning-maker can, however, choose to re-evaluate these resources, to assess their value for the immediate contexts and to select according to criteria, context and design. Recognition thus also entails self-reflexivity and the ability to understand this notion of semiotic choice. As an example of how choice operates, I will look at a student’s text that combines writing and information graphics. The example in figure 1 below is taken from a PhD thesis in medical virology in the Health Sciences. The aim of the PhD is to investigate the therapeutic role of two vaccinations (the ‘humanized recombinant vaccinia virus complement control protein’ (hrVCP) and the ‘vaccinia infected mammalian cell derived authentic VCP’) in Ischemia/Reperfusion (I/R) injury of the kidney in rats. The choice of information graphic and how to configure it is important in order to construct an argument in this particular context. In this graphic, the argument is that the injured and treated (VCP/hrVCP) group of rats recovered better than the injured and untreated (PBS) group. The confidence interval information, using the standard error of the mean (SEM) in the chart, allows for the comparison of the three groups. The three groups include the treated rats, untreated rats and the sham or control group which comprises rats which have not been injured or treated. The label on the horizontal axis is ‘groups’. The subjects, namely rats, are removed in this label, resulting in abstraction of the chart from a particular context, which is characteristic of scientific discourse. The student has chosen a bar chart with confidence intervals to represent his data. He could have chosen a table format, which would have impacted on the type of information it is possible to display. For instance, displaying the sample size would have been more likely in a table, whereas its absence in the bar chart is not so obvious. The chart comprises blue bars on a grey background which is the default design in Excel. There are a host of other design choices that the student could have made, such as using different colours, different spacing between bars, a more finely calibrated vertical axis for ease of comparison. However, the mailto:Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za E-mail: Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za 4 bulky size and shape of the bar does give more visual weight to the argument than a single point would and the wide spacing between the bars creates a clear distinction between the different groups. Figure 1. Extract from a PhD thesis in Medical Virology in the Health Sciences As a counterpoint to these ‘safe’ representational choices, it is worth thinking about information graphics which are composed somewhat differently. By calling his book Information is Beautiful, McCandless (2009) draws overt attention to the ‘aesthetic’ potential of information graphics. There are design choices to be made here in terms of size, shape, colour, and composition in order to represent an argument to a particular audience in the most apt way. The representation in figure 2 is also a comparison. McCandless compares tons of carbon emitted annually and uses iconic shapes for comparison rather than rectangular ones. However, these shapes have not been scaled to size, indicating a rhetorical decision rather than a statistical one. Because the representation is organized in spatial rather than linear terms, one could tell many stories from the information, not necessarily in any particular order. However, by placing the tree in the upper left corner, the relationship of it to the other mailto:Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za E-mail: Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za 5 Figure 2. Tonnes of carbon emitted annually (McCandless 2009, 26) Reproduced with permission from David McCandless (c) 2009. categories or objects is encouraged. The choice of items to compare (individual house, car, air travel and large human) reflects the argument which the author wishes to make, namely that individual and excessive consumption cause carbon emissions and have a harmful effect on the environment. Whilst recognizing that this information graphic is embedded in particular socio-political discourses and realized in journalistic genres, it is useful in mailto:Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za E-mail: Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za 6 demonstrating a different kind of authorial agency and power-differential than the student- produced graphic. The representational choices made here may not be appropriate in an academic environment, whereas they may function well in the social domain where form and readability need not be as closely aligned. How and why people choose to represent from a range of options points to the notion of design; the process of giving shape to the interests of the sign-maker for an assumed audience using the available semiotic resources (Bezemer and Kress 2008: 174). These choices are always expressions of ideology and power – what choices were made and for what purposes? Multimodal classroom discourse as sign production, reception and transformation, can thus be understood as student’s active engagement with the semiotic resources available to them at a particular moment in a specific socio-cultural context (Kress 1997). Bearing this in mind, I will now focus on exploring some ways of designing multimodal classrooms for social justice, looking at examples from different educational sites in South Africa. The examples refer to a number of contexts in Higher Education and a High School poetry project, yet the principles could be applied to classrooms in other contexts, spanning different age ranges. Burring boundaries between domains. One way of creating more semiotically open classrooms is to set tasks that work across disciplines and defined domains of knowledge, as well as across a range of modes, media and genres. Bernstein (1996) points out that power is maintained and relayed through the creation of boundaries between practices, and it is often in ‘mixed’ forms where power is played out. Questioning or reinterpreting some standard generic conventions can signal an encounter of diverse knowledges and differently organized social worlds. An interesting example of this kind of blurring of boundaries between disciplinary, professional, private and public domains is a project in a fourth year pharmacology course (Weiss, forthcoming). In the project, students produce a pamphlet or other Health Promotion materials, get feedback from a patient and write a reflective critique on the process, including their design, content and ethical considerations. The aim is to enable medical students to learn how to adapt and personalize clinical information for individual patients from diverse educational, language, economic and socio-cultural backgrounds. Producing health promotion materials requires students to draw on resources from a range of domains, mailto:Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za E-mail: Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za 7 including clinical environments which provide access to academic knowledge about disease as well as professional environments that construct ‘ways of being a doctor’. Weiss argues that a social semiotic analysis of the student-produced texts is useful to identify underlying assumptions (in this case, assumptions about sexual behaviour). Recognizing these assumptions is important in order to feed back into the design of the medical curriculum. She looks at how the student pamphlets on contraception construct views on reproductive responsibility, male-female relationships, doctor-patient relationships, disease, morality. This is done by pushing the boundaries of the pamphlet genre which is realized through images, layout, writing, as well as ‘interactivity’. For example, one pamphlet requires the reader to ‘unbuckle the belt’ in order to open the pamphlet, which has a tag on the front, ‘Ready for sex?’ These views on contraception often co-exist alongside contemporary discourses of the market place. The students thus draw on semiotic and discursive resources in professional, private and public domains for meaning-making. In the above project, recognition is linked to development and ‘transformed practice’ (New London Group 2000). Student resources are validated and are used to provide access to the professional discourses valued in academic educational contexts as well as the medical profession. Weiss argues that the process of ‘conscious design’ within a framework of social semiotics represents a way of developing patient-centered communication practices amongst medical students, as well as preparing the students for the challenges of a multicultural and socially diverse working environment. We can see that this multimodal classroom stresses the making and production of meaning, rather than the acquisition of received knowledge or critique of received knowledge. Fundamental to the notion of multimodality employed in a social justice agenda is the concept of transformation, that meaning-making does not so much involve use of a system, as the transformation of available resources. Harnessing students’ resources In designing multimodal classrooms for access and social justice, the discourse and knowledge of the discipline should be made available, whilst students’ resources are simultaneously utilized and validated. Projects are not simply springboards for students, but are a serious interrogation and utilization of students’ representational resources. This enables a shift in power relations in the classroom from top-down imposition to negotiation and discussion. Also, discursive and generic conventions are brought into focus in order to show mailto:Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za E-mail: Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za 8 what kinds of social situations produce them, and what the meanings of these social situations are. Only resources which are visible can become available as elements in conscious design processes. In this way, different ways of thinking and practice in representation become available as resources for students and there is an expansion of the repertoire of resources in order to create semiotically open classrooms. This includes multilingualism, indigenous and local cultural and semiotic practices. Some of my own work explores ways of harnessing students’ resources in different disciplinary sites in Higher Education. I have looked at ways of establishing a dialogue between less regulated spaces in the curriculum and the texts that emerge from them, and the more regulated genres of the curriculum so that students’ representational resources can be utilized in innovative ways. An example of this is a Symbolic Object project in a first year Communication Course in an engineering foundation programme. In the project, students identify everyday objects that have symbolic meanings and examine these in a range of physical, cultural and communicational contexts. The aim of this pedagogical intervention was to use objects and symbolism in order to engage with questions of diversity and identity. Objects are seen as a way of eliciting student narratives, exploring dynamic and conflicting cultural practices, highlighting notions of change and focusing on recontextualization of meaning in new contexts (Archer 2007). The objects the students identified were often aspirational like a microwave in a community without electricity, and the steps at Jameson Hall, a popular place to hang out on our campus, but also the place where you graduate. Various religious objects were identified, and a number of animals, including a goat and the rituals around slaughtering. Many of these objects indexed change in one way or another, and highlighted shifts and contradictions in certain cultural practices. For instance, beer in South African society has different meanings for different contexts. According to the students, it highlights issues of generation, class, cultural groupings, economics and crime. In terms of generational aspects, traditional beer is not drunk by young people because it symbolises ‘manhood’. On the other hand, ‘modern’ beer is drunk more by young people. The students highlighted that beer drinking culture differs across groups in our society: Whites drink beer to celebrate something … Black people especially the Zulus, use beer (traditional beer) when they have feasts ... to communicate with their ancestors. mailto:Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za E-mail: Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za 9 This example shows how a project like the Symbolic Object intervention could draw on students’ socio-cultural resources in order to raise questions around diversity and identity in the classroom. The students produced a short research project around these issues, drawing on multimodal semiotic resources to do so. By advocating a curriculum that sets up a dialogue with students’ resources in order to ‘harnesses’ them, I do not mean simply using these resources, but encouraging students to critically interrogate them. I have examined the ways in which the resources used in less regulated curriculum spaces can be utilized in more formal, high-stakes assessment curriculum tasks, and looked at how underlying systems of classification transfer across contexts, for instance from the ‘mythical’ to the ‘scientific’ where part-whole structures and transformative processes operate (See Archer 2010 for an argument that mystical knowledge may have the same function as science in particular communities, as both are about constructing relations between elements in the natural world). The notions of convention and change that a pedagogical intervention such as the Symbolic Object project raises are important to explore. ‘Change’ need not necessarily mean ‘loss’, but needs to be conceived of as additive. We need to be aware of and respect cultural norms and values, but at the same time, begin to look at these critically and with constructive lenses. Developing metalanguages of reflection In order to development an environment of recognition, it is useful to be able to theorize and understand resources using a metalanguage. A metalanguage can “identify and explain difference between texts, and relate these to the contexts of culture and situation in which they seem to work” (NLG 2000, 24). Metalanguages are thus important in achieving conscious awareness of the nature of the resources being used and for this reason, they can feed into assessment criteria. However, complex metalanguages can be daunting for many students and could hinder rather than enhance the learning experience. Thesen (2001) suggests that rather than propose an entirely new vocabulary and new ways of understanding the world, a metalanguage should serve as “an index of discourse – ways of verbalising what you know in relation to other ways of knowing” (143). In a study on technical drawing in a civil engineering diploma, Simpson (forthcoming) stages a two part argument involving metalanguage and access. He argues that the semiotic domain mailto:Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za E-mail: Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za 10 of Civil Engineering drawing is particularly stable, and thus governed by sometimes invisible rules and conventions. Some students may be less familiar with these ‘taken-for-granted’ ways of drawing than others, which could disadvantage them in the classroom. Firstly, he identifies and makes explicit key resources which are used in drawing, including line thickness, line continuity, the type of lead used, conventions governing the representation of particular materials such as screed or concrete or stone. Secondly, he develops a way of talking about drawing in order to highlight the often unconscious norms and conventions that students become socialized into. This includes aspects like modality or the credibility of the drawing which he defines in terms of criterial partiality, composition, framing and abstraction. It also includes conventional practices such as labelling, dimensioning, framing and accuracy. Here, the metalanguage developed provides a way of making explicit the norms and conventions operating in the tightly regulated domain of engineering drawing. This may be useful in enabling student access into this domain. I have argued elsewhere (Archer 2012) that we need to expand the notion of a ‘metalanguage’ to that of ‘metaforms’. By ‘metaform’, I refer to a means of description and analysis that can work across modes. Although it is more common to use the written mode to reflect on the visual, it is possible for an image to reflect on another image or on writing (as in satirical cartoons and various kinds of culture jamming). Using these kinds of ‘metaforms’ for reflection in the classroom could ignite critical thought and dialogue. Teaching students how to do textual analysis can draw attention to social boundaries and inequality. Textual analysis enables access to understanding and debunking of dominant discourses, rather than seeing these as fixed and natural. Texts reflect and recycle different discourses. Some of these discourses may complement each other, and others may compete with each other or represent conflicting interests or ideologies. This is Bakhtin’s (1981) notion of dialogism, the recognition of the polyvocality of any sign. In culture jamming, for example, the tension between these competing discourses is foregrounded in order to pass critical commentary on a social issue. Multimodal classrooms can open up spaces for interrogating which texts are valued and why, thus highlighting relations of power. Creating less regulated curriculum spaces In designing multimodal classrooms for social justice, it is important to include less regulated spaces in order to increase students’ choices and allow scope for reflection. These include mailto:Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za E-mail: Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za 11 physical as well as virtual spaces, such as online chats. In these spaces, students can experiment with multimodal representation, draw on a range of discourses and employ humour or irony. They can draw on primary discourses as well as secondary discourses to create metalanguages to make sense of the curriculum. By way of illustrating the power of these less regulated spaces, I will briefly look at a project which drew on African popular culture to revitalize the poetry curriculum at a High School in Soweto (Newfield and Maugedzo 2006). Newfield’s work on language and literacy and literature education in South Africa has combined multimodal classroom and textual practices with social justice education. The mainstream approach to the teaching and learning of poetry in South Africa is ‘analysis’. In this project, Newfield and Maugedzo shifted the curriculum focus from analysis to composition, which enabled the students to produce poetry in different ways – as a spoken form, as performance, and even as embroidered cloth. Changing the audience, meant the students could write poetry to friends, and, finally, even produce an alternative poetry anthology to the school anthology. It was the ‘freeing up’ of poetry in a low stakes informal environment using multimodal means that made this particular pedagogical intervention such a success. Here hegemonic language and pedagogic practices were challenged, whilst simultaneously providing access to dominant language practices. This example illustrates how less regulated curriculum spaces can enable students to draw on and experiment with a range of genres and modes. This can open up opportunities for exchange of cultural and personal knowledge, and create opportunities for students who may have been marginalized in the classroom to find a legitimate voice. Challenges in designing multimodal classrooms Although there are many instances of multimodal pedagogical interventions and research projects that have resulted in social change, I would also like to sound a cautionary note. For instance, when some student teachers at a South African university were asked how they would employ the ideas around multimodal pedagogies in the classroom, they evidenced confusion around underlying notions of culture. For instance, the following ‘learning outcomes’ were listed by one student teacher for an activity around symbolic objects in the classroom: • The learners will be able to use materials and objects to show how they have grown/changed. mailto:Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za E-mail: Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za 12 • Learners will be able to identify different clothes for different cultures. These are very different orders of outcome revealing conflicting views on culture. The first outcome is about culture as change, and the second about culture as stasis. The notion of culture as static and not about change and flux was common amongst this group of student teachers and is reflected in the following statement: This classroom activity can be introduced by asking learners to tell us more about their cultures. They can also wear different cultural clothes on a certain day, to learn more about cultural differences. So that they can appreciate the diversity of culture. They can also bring different food used in their cultures. The tragedy of this proposed classroom activity is that it lapses into a crude multiculturalism where clothes and food signify ‘culture’ which is seen as having distinct boundaries. Even if student-teachers ostensibly talked of culture as a ‘resource’ (Thornton 1988), rather than as a ‘thing’, their thinking often lapsed into basic forms of compartmentalization, essentialism and stereotyping, which has proved to be so dangerous in our past history. I think what this exercise revealed to me is how carefully this subject matter needs to be handled in the classroom, and also, how deeply entrenched stereotypical thinking is in South African society which continues to be polarized. It is clear that simply including a range of modes and text types in the curriculum, does not necessarily enable student access. This kind of ‘mode determinism’ could lead to instrumentalism and the kind of crude multiculturalism demonstrated above. It is worth noting that the classroom is always multimodal. What I am proposing here is a broader social semiotic approach that sees modes in a particular way. I am not proposing that the use of different modes necessarily generates the ideological and epistemological shifts in the classroom. It is not the broadening out of modes that has these effects, but rather the deeper ideological issues that underpin their uses in these ways. Other challenges could include harnessing the energy and emotions that are sometimes unleashed in these kinds of less regulated spaces. For instance, in Stein’s (2008) Olifantsvlei Fresh Stories project the children gave horrifying accounts of violent incidents from the impoverished, politicized and violent environments in which they lived. Containing and framing those experiences is vital for students to process them both individually and collectively. This is important in terms of recognizing and harnessing students’ resources in order to ultimately produce critical and humane citizens. mailto:Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za E-mail: Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za 13 Final comments This paper has reflected on ways of designing multimodal classrooms in relation to power and social justice. I have argued for the importance of this as there is still differential access to economic, educational and cultural resources in our society and institutional discursive practices in education can serve to exclude particular groups. My main argument is that we need to see recognition in relation to access in the broadest sense and not just access to existing norms. If we understand recognition as simply noticing or theorizing resources, this runs the risk of institutionalizing situated practice. While it is educationally sound to validate local practices and resources, access to dominant practices has to be provided at the same time (Janks 2000). Thinking of classroom discourse as socio-historically situated, draws attention to the contested nature of dominant conventions. Of particular interest in terms of social justice is the extent to which we can create unregulated spaces in order to enable a range of student resources to emerge, as well as the ways in which we can enable access to dominant forms in multimodal ways. Equally important, is the development and use of accessible metalanguages of “reflective generalization that describe the form, content and function of the discourses of practice” (New London Group 2000: 24) to enable students to discuss and critique texts across contexts. The interventions described in this paper acknowledge “learners as agentive, resourceful and creative meaning-makers” (Stein and Newfield 2006: 8). They place a strong emphasis on student ‘interest’ and agency. Classrooms which both draw on and validate students’ practices, resources and discourses are invaluable, as they enable students to interrogate their past situations and aspirations, to reflect on dominant norms and practices, whilst providing access to these at the same time. References Archer, A. 2012. Writing as design. Enabling access to academic discourse in a multimodal environment. South African Journal of Higher Education 26, 3: 411 – 421. Archer, A. 2010. Shamanism and Science: Reciprocal curriculum as transformative. Education as Change. 14, 1. 61 – 75. mailto:Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za E-mail: Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za 14 Archer, A. 2007. ‘No goats in the mother city’: Using Symbolic Objects to help students talk about diversity and change. English in Education 41, 1: 7 – 20. Archer, A. 2006. A multimodal approach to academic ‘literacies’: problematizing the visual/verbal divide. Language and Education 20, 6: 449 – 462. Bakhtin, M. 1981. Discourse in the novel. (M. Holquist ed. and trans). The Dialogic Imagination. Four Essays by M. Bakhtin. Austin: University of Texas Press. Bernstein, B. 1996. Pedagogy, Symbolic Control and Identity. Theory, Research, Critique. London: Taylor and Francis. Bezemer, J. and Kress, G. 2008. Writing in multimodal texts. A social semiotic account of designs for learning. Written Communication 25, 2: 166 – 195. Harrop-Allin, S. 2011. Playing with Barbie: exploring South African township children’s games as resources for pedagogy. In L. Green. (ed.) Learning, Teaching and Musical Identity: Voices across Cultures. Bloomington: University of Indiana Press. 156 – 169. Janks, H. 2000. Domination, access, diversity and design: a synthesis for Critical Literacy education. Educational Review 52, 2: 175 – 186. McCandless, D. 2009. Information is Beautiful. London: Collins. Newfield, D. 2011. Multimodality, social justice and becoming a really South African democracy: case studies from language classrooms. In Social Justice Language Teacher Education, ed. M. Hawkins. 23 – 48. Bristol, UK: Multilingual Matters. 23 – 48. Newfield, D. and Maungedzo, R. 2006. Moblising and Modalising Poetry in a Soweto Classroom. English Studies in Africa 49, 1: 71-93. mailto:Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za E-mail: Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za 15 New London Group. 2000. A Pedagogy of Multiliteracies: Designing Social Futures. In Multiliteracies. Literacy Learning and the Design of Social Futures, eds B. Cope and M. Kalantzis. London and New York: Routledge. Simpson, Z. (forthcoming) Resources, representation and regulation in Civil Engineering Drawing: An autoethnographic perspective. In Multimodal approaches to research and pedagogy: Recognition, resources and access, eds. A. Archer and D. Newfield. Routledge. Stein, P. 2008. Multimodal pedagogies in diverse classrooms, representation, right and resources. London, New York: Routledge. Stein, P. and Newfield, D. 2006. Multiliteracies and Multimodality in English in Education in Africa: Mapping the Terrain. English Studies in Africa 49. 1: 1 – 22. Thesen, L. 2001. Modes, Literacies and Power: A University Case Study. In Language and Education 14, 2 and 3. 132 – 145. Thesen, L. 2007. Breaking the frame: lectures, ritual and academic literacies. Journal of Applied Linguistics 4, 1: 33 – 53. Thornton, R. 1988. Culture: A contemporary definition. In The Uses and Abuses of Political Concepts, eds. E. Boonzaier and J. Sharp. Cape Town and Johannesburg: David Phillip. Weiss, R. (forthcoming). Multimodality and Medicine. In Multimodal approaches to research and pedagogy: Recognition, resources and access, eds. A. Archer and D. Newfield. Routledge. mailto:Arlene.Archer@uct.ac.za work_cl7y7fwdzzhormjhvogvhrlp3i ---- 1 Buridan and the Circumstances of Justice (on the Implications of the Rational Unsolvability of Certain Co-ordination Problems) 1 Duncan MacIntosh, Dalhousie University Published as: Duncan MacIntosh, "Buridan and the Circumstances of Justice (On the Implications of the Rational Unsolvability of Certain Co-ordination Problems)", Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 73, No. 2 (1992), pp. 150-173. Introduction Many problems of rationality and morality involve agents in a partial conflict of interest: one agent can do well only if another does poorly. The paradigm is the Prisoner's Dilemma (PD). Some commentators think it rational for PD agents to compromise, agreeing to voluntarily so co-ordinate their choices that each will do fairly well, better than if each straightforwardly pursued his individual interest. Thus David Gauthier thinks that PD agents should conditionally dispose themselves to co-operate and then co-operate with the like-disposed. But as Howard Sobel points out 2 , in some PDs it seems impossible, directly anyway, to voluntarily comply with a compromise strategy because some of these strategies do not specify each agent's behavioral obligations. The strategy may require each agent to do something 50% of the time, for instance, but not say what each is to do this time. Sobel suggests, then, that voluntarily pursuing a compromise strategy would not always be an available alternative to say, Hobbesian Leviathan solutions, where the agents ally with a state which would then dictate actions to each agent and enforce the edict. 3 I here defend Gauthier's proposal from this worry, showing how it can be rational for the agents to use randomizers to make their behavioral obligations determinate. 4 But I then consider a deeper problem for both Gauthian and Hobbesian solutions. Both in effect reduce partial conflicts (PDs) to non-conflictual co-ordination problems (CPs). It is widely thought that rational agents can solve CPs simply by choosing by mutual fiat one among several optimizing co-ordinated patterns of choice. The only exceptions are supposed to be when the agents can't communicate, or lack certain common knowledge. Then, their only hope is that a "salient" will cause a non-rational solution. But I prove that some CPs are rationally unsolvable even absent circumstantial or informational impediments to agreement on a solution. Here, the problem is not circumstances, but rationality: As normally understood it cannot guarantee co-operative solutions to CPs or PDs, and many precepts of contractarian moral rationalism must therefore be false. I suggest some re-conceptions of rationality to alleviate some of these difficulties, but even with rationality so amended, whether rational co-operation and morality is possible is often a matter of sheer luck, not rational choice; and even such rational solutions as are possible depend on non-rational accidents. This first part of this paper expounds Gauthier's theories; the second, a modification Sobel thinks necessary to keep them general. The third discusses some of Sobel's 2 supposed counter-examples to the generality of Gauthier's claims about co-operation. The last considers possibly irresolvable problems for the implementation of both Gauthian and Hobbesian systems. The larger issue is just what sorts of joint arrangements for mutually advantageous behavior rational agents can make simply by rational voluntary agreement. Resolving this question requires a new conception of the rationality of both individuals and groups. And it requires us to understand differently the rational foundations for morality as conceived by contractarian moral rationalists, who think morality is derivable from rationality (as explicated in the formal sciences of decision and game theory). I Gauthier 5 Gauthier aimed to resolve an apparent conflict between rationality and morality. To be rational is to maximize one's individual expected utility, to be moral, to refrain from maximizing. So how can it be rational to be moral? Gauthier took this apparent conflict to be modeled in the one-shot PD: Each agent prefers in descending order, unilateral confession, mutual non-confession, mutual confession, unilateral non-confession. If one agent confesses, depending on what the other agent does, the first agent's best outcome is his first best, his worst, his third; if the first agent doesn't confess, his best outcome is his second, his worst, his fourth. If his actions are causally independent of the other's, no matter what the other does, the first does better (maximizes by) confessing; so if he is rational, he will confess. Ditto for the other agent. But if both confess, each achieves only his third best outcome; if only each had refrained, each would have obtained his second best. Gauthier thinks this represents the structure of circumstances of justice, of choice problems creating moral issues and admitting moral resolutions. Moral issues are partial conflicts of interests, moral resolutions, socially optimal, mutually advantageous solutions to those conflicts. Here the agents are conflicted because neither can get his best outcome without the other getting his worst. The non-moral solution is for each to seek his maximal individual advantage, the moral one, for both to seek their joint optimal mutual advantage. This is for both to adhere to a moral rule. In a standard PD that would be: Do not confess. The defining property of moral rules: Each individual is better off if all comply with them than if all deviate, but better off still if he deviates whether or not others comply. If complying is "co-operating," deviating, "defecting," the original problem of how it can be rational to be moral is: How can it be rational to co-operate when it is individually more advantageous to defect? Gauthier observed that while each agent has a powerful incentive to defect (confess), each, to avoid the disaster of mutual defection, has a more powerful incentive to arrange that all agents co-operate (obey the rule of non-confession). Each would prefer such arrangements even should they secure his own co-operation. But because of the ever- present temptation each has to defect, Hobbes thought the only efficacious such arrangement would be a state, an external force penalizing defectors. Each agent would then refrain from defecting to avoid the penalties, which make it maximizing and so straightforwardly rational to co-operate. 3 But Gauthier thinks the conflict can be resolved without the costs and coercions of the state. For he thinks agents can rationally adopt dispositions constraining them from always performing individually maximizing actions, and that an action is rational if it expresses a disposition it was rational to adopt. When facing a PD, it is most advantageous for the agent to have whatever disposition will most likely induce others to co-operate while yet allowing him to defect as much as possible. Given perfect information, this is the one which disposes one to co-operation just where, did it not, one would probably be defected against, but since it does, provokes another to co-operate, otherwise allowing one to defect. It is thus the maximizing and so rational disposition to adopt. In choosing from this disposition one will co-operate whenever one meets a similar agent, otherwise defect. Such agents are conditional co-operators or "Constrained Maximizers" (CMers), conditional because their dispositions induce them to co-operate only with the like disposed; constrained because their dispositions sometimes prevent them from performing individually maximizing actions (from "straightforwardly maximizing"--"SMing"--and so from always defecting), and instead sometimes make them perform jointly optimizing actions. To adopt such a disposition is to adopt a strategy for making further choices, a "joint strategy," i.e., a way of choosing where one performs a certain action expecting it to be part of a certain outcome whose other part is to be a certain action of another agent. (To straightforwardly maximize--to "SM"--is to follow an "individual strategy", one where one performs a certain action regardless of what action the other agent is expected to perform.) To act co-operatively is to act as required by a joint co-operative strategy. In general, a CMer is disposed to co-operate (to base his actions on some joint strategy or practice) and will co-operate, (a) where everyone's co-operating (i.e., everyone's complying with this strategy) yields him no less utility than everyone's defecting, (b) where his share of the benefits of co-operation are at least fair to him by minimax standards 6 , and (c) where, because others are similarly disposed, his expected utility from his co-operating is higher than from everyone defecting (i.e., using individual strategies). 7 Absent (a), there is no point to adopting a CM disposition. Absent (b), one could do better by holding out until others concede to one one's fair share. Absent (c), to co- operate would be to have been suckered, for there was no guarantee others would reciprocate. 8 In general then, Gauthier thinks that in the circumstances of justice, each agent should "internalize a principle of action, that, followed by everyone, leads to an outcome that is both optimal and fair, in receiving the voluntary agreement of all," and that each should co-operate from that disposition with others like disposed. 9 II Some Possible Worries Sobel thinks it false that a rational agent will co-operate (i.e., do his part in an optimality- producing joint strategy of choice) whenever (a)-(c) are satisfied. 10 For it may be that while there is a rule (or strategy) everyone's complying with which would optimize were there a clear way to comply with it, the rule is not, by itself, specific about each agent's behavioral obligations. E.g., imagine I always prefer going to the movies with you first, going alone second; you always prefer going to the library with me first, alone second. 11 4 We can't both always get our first choice. But we can do better than always going out alone by splitting the difference, each of us netting a utility intermediate between us always getting our first or second best outcomes. Each of us would be crazy to yield to the other's first choice or to demand that he do the same, more than half the time. But it is maximizing for us each to conditionally commit to the optimizing joint strategy of going to the movies together half the evenings, the library the other half. Fine. We each so commit. But where should we go tonight? The optimizing rule does not say. Since it prescribes no action to either of us, we can not co-operate. We need a randomizing process. Perhaps we can flip a coin, agreeing to abide by the result. 12 Or perhaps we can go to an official coin-flipper. 13 The lesson Sobel draws 14 : a rational CMer should co- operate only given (a)-(c) and, (d) where either the joint strategy itself imposes determinate obligations on each, or does so when "partially implemented" (i.e., when it is decided for each agent how he should act, in the case at hand) by a randomizing process actually performed. Otherwise, each agent should individually SM (i.e., defect), since there is nothing he can do to act on the joint strategy. We can distinguish 15 between individual pure strategies (e.g., where an agent confesses no matter what), individual mixed strategies (e.g., where an agent confesses 50% of the time), joint pure strategies (e.g., where the agents co-ordinate, each always non-confessing), and joint mixed strategies (e.g., where the agents co-ordinate, simultaneously non-confessing 50% of the time). The trouble is that mixed strategies may not dictate actions except when "partially implemented," i.e., when how to choose has been referred to a lottery actually performed. We will consider now two possible counter-examples to Gauthier's theses. In the first, absent an authoritative randomizer there is no dictated action and so even those committed to a joint strategy will defect. In the second, agents are committed to a joint strategy, but one the implementation of which for each agent (again, absent a lottery) depends on what the other will probably do. But then neither can individually decide what to do, so neither will co-operate. III The Cases Case 1 Sobel offers the following "stretched-PD" as a prima face counter-example to Gauthier's claim that rational CMers will co-operate in all PDs. 16 Here, each agent prefers unilateral confession (in which he gets 100 utiles), mutual non-confession (3 utiles), mutual confession (2), unilateral non-confession (1). The "stretch" is in the wild pay-off difference between unilateral confession and all other outcomes. This makes the expected utility of taking a chance on achieving unilateral confession higher than for arranging joint non-confession; it makes it rational for each agent to conditionally commit to a joint mixed rather than pure strategy. For each has a minimax claim to 50.5 expected utilities (half of the total utilities produced by failing at unilateral confession and achieving only unilateral non-confession, plus half of those produced by succeeding at unilateral confession). The pure joint strategy of mutual non-confession only gets each agent 3 5 utiles, far from their minimax. Thus, by (b), neither will commit to it. Each can only get his minimax by both agents choosing by a joint mixed strategy which uses a single randomizer dictating each agent's choice, i.e., a joint randomizer dictating confession to each agent 50% of the time (or confession on a given occasion with a 50% chance). But suppose there is no randomizer. Without one, committing to that co-operative strategy underdetermines the co-operative action each should perform in nature. Thus each CMer should confess--by (d)--whatever the other may do. Thus even CMers will not always "co-operate" in nature, nor always produce optimal and fair outcomes, contra-Gauthier. Thus, he cannot, as he would like to, give alternative solutions to all of Hobbes'. In nature, and absent an authoritative randomizer, there may be no determinate co-operative choice for a joint strategy; so even CMers should sometimes defect. Reply It seems initially that we can make short work of these worries. First, while to co-operate we must sometimes use a lottery, the incentive to co-operate also rationalizes us in using one to implement co-operation. Thus even if there is now no authoritative lottery, it would be rational, for all we have seen so far, for us simply to agree on a lottery method, to run it, and to abide by its result. Second, this is not us jointly allying with a Hobbesian Leviathan, since, by hypothesis, the lottery is costless and we do not need anyone to enforce compliance with it. For were it rational to co-operate simpliciter, other things equal that would still be rational where it consists in acting per the lottery. Third, if by "nature" we mean "no co-ordination," then of course we cannot there co- ordinate. But Gauthier never thought we would. He is trying to rationalize us moving out of a state of nature in which we individually SM, into a situation where we co-ordinate, optimizing conjointly under voluntary mutual constraints. Fourth, if we cannot find or agree on a joint lottery process, the rational alternative is not SMing and mutual defection. For we might each have our own lottery devices, and even if we can't agree to jointly abide by either, we might still be able to agree to individually abide by our personal lotteries. 17 We could each resolve that instead of always confessing, we will each flip a coin to decide whether to confess provided the other is also conditionally disposed to choose using his coin. We will then each confess 50% of the time, achieving unilateral confession (and each other outcome) 25% of the time. This gives us each an expected utility for following the joint strategy of us each following the individual strategy of choosing by our individual lotteries of 26.5 (the sum of 25% of the utilities of each possible outcome). This is still a joint strategy, following it is a kind of co-operation, and resorting to it is not resorting to a Leviathan. Fifth, if neither joint nor individual lotteries are available it is still not rational for us to SM. For we would each still do better conditionally committing to acting from the disposition to comply with the strategy of jointly non-confessing with a like-committed agent. And that is still a joint strategy, acting on it still a kind of co-operation. Sixth, while it might be objected that Gauthier cannot accept any of these alternatives because none have an expected utility near the original minimax of 50.5, I think he could 6 accept all of them in their circumstances. For what the minimax point is surely depends on what options there are. If there is no way of achieving a minimax of 50.5 in the circumstances, it is not there the minimax. Rather, the minimax is whatever optimum circumstances permit. E.g., were there a machine which would furnish us each with all that we desire if we each gave it all that we have, our minimax would be all that we want. But absent such a machine it is absurd to say that in our present circumstances the minimax is "all that we want." So if circumstances permit a joint lottery the minimax is 50.5; if only individual lotteries, 26.5; if neither, 3. If no co-operative strategy is available, the question is moot. 18 Lessons: First, use of lotteries is, where possible, rational if needed for co-operation. Second, it is not necessarily recourse to a state. Third, many joint strategies, pure and mixed, count as co-operation. We have not shown a PD has no co-operative solution until we have shown none work. Fourth, what counts as the optimal and fair solution to a PD depends on what the circumstances afford to resolve it. Case 2 In Sobel's next case 19 , there is no mutual advantage to the agents so co-ordinating as that one agent does what the other does not. There is mutual advantage to each doing the same, but differential advantage to each depending on which of two possible same-type actions are performed. An example would be a PD where one agent's preferences would have him get 3 utiles if both non-confess, 2 if both confess, 0 from everything else; the other agent, 3 from if both confess, 2 if both non-confess, otherwise 0: one agent gets more utility if both non-confess, the other, if both confess. Thus they differ on which joint solution they favor--both confessing or both non-confessing--though each favors either over individual strategies. Reply This case presents several difficulties. First, while CMers would commit to either each of them confessing or each not, that commitment does not say which action each should perform; should each confess, or each not? And neither can act on the joint strategy until this is settled. Without a lottery it seems then that they cannot implement the joint strategy, so neither agent can act co-operatively. (Couldn't either agent provoke the other to do his part in the strategy most favored by the first agent by the first agent doing his part in his favorite strategy first? For then the second agent always does better going along with the first agent's preemptive move than not. Better that both do the same thing, even if one agent has usurped the prerogative of deciding what it will be. Unfortunately, if both think this way, as they must if both are rational and if it is the rational way to think, each will race to make his favorite choice, attempting to force it on the other, the result, a failure of co-ordination. Since both agents are presumed to be well-informed and rational, both would see this and its consequences, and both will pause and attempt to arrange non-preemptive co-ordination.) Even were both agents committed to a joint strategy, to choosing like each other, and even if they sought to resolve the dilemma 7 without a lottery, by fiat, neither agent could rationally decide how to choose unless he knew how the other was likely to choose. Since nothing makes it more rational to choose one way over the other for either agent, neither can ever make a rational choice. But a lottery would clearly resolve this. And since a lottery would be instrumental to a strategy to which it is maximizing to commit, everything equal it would be maximizing and so rational to commit to compliance with a lottery. But there is a differential advantage to the agents in the outcome of the lottery. Thus if it says both must confess, the second agent gets one more utile than if both don't confess and vice versa. What is the minimax? How can a joint strategy attain it? Ideally the agents would commit to splitting the advantage, their minimax an even split. Were that impossible, there is still no problem, for the initial randomization of behaviors distributes the advantage, equalizing expected utilities, and while one agent must gain more actual utility, the other cannot object. For there is no other available more fair procedure, each had equal chance at the advantage, and without this process the "looser" does even worse. But what if no joint randomizer is available? Then there can't be co-ordination. (Well, not quite. Suppose that, though the agents had no agreed joint randomizer, they each had individual randomizers. It would advantage each agent to conditionally commit to the joint strategy of each agent choosing whether to confess or non-confess by each using his individual randomizer, for then they at least have a 50% chance of attaining one of the equilibrium outcomes, and each agent has a 25% chance of attaining his most preferred outcome. While if each simply followed the individual strategy of choosing his half of his most preferred outcome, each would have no chance of attaining either equilibrium outcome. But of course, it could well happen that neither equilibrium results in the outcome produced by these individual randomizations. In any case, let us stipulate that the agents also lack individual randomizers.) But then neither would Gauthier think there ought to be co-operation (i.e., successful co-ordination in producing one of the equilibrium outcomes). For here (a) and (c) are not satisfied: No (available) joint strategies would maximize if agents chose on their basis over SMing; no action is advantageous over the one the SMer would perform were all others SMers. So Gauthier need not solve this case any more than he must solve PDs where agents are not given pre- interactive information on each others' dispositions, nor a pre-interactive chance to amend them. It is not a circumstance of justice; unsurprising, for a crucial requisite to its being one--a joint randomizer or individual randomizers--is stipulated unavailable. It is not the game's pay-off structure which prevents it from being a circumstance of justice, but that absent a lottery (or lotteries), even with the best will in the world the agents cannot attain an equilibrium outcome, cannot choose expecting a minimax higher than for individual strategies. But is Hobbesianism superior here? One might think so. For Hobbes might tell us to ally with a Leviathan who would then impose a solution. The Leviathan might use a lottery available only to Him to decide whether to impose confession or non-confession, and if we knew this, it would individually maximize for us each to conditionally commit to gambling with the Leviathan. Or He might simply have an arbitrary, secret policy of enforcing, say, non-confession. It would, again, advantage each of us to take a gamble and ally ourselves with Him over us SMing no matter what his policy, even though, one 8 of us will be marginally disadvantaged by it, whichever it is. (His policy must be secret; otherwise, if it is a condition of His existing as a Leviathan that we both ally with Him, the agent who knew himself to be marginally disadvantaged by the Leviathan's policy would have a stake in holding out, breaking the deal. Nothing would rationally compel his acquiescence in the Leviathan's solution if his preferred solution could still be attained by the other agent's agreeing to go along with it. Rather, the old problem returns: should the agents go with joint confession or joint non-confession? But now the problem takes this form: should they go with the Leviathan's policy or make their own pact?) 20 But this is not really a fair alternative to Gauthian solutions. For one thing, just as the Leviathan may have an arbitrary policy, so might one of us (one either hard-wired or involving an additional preference). Oddly, it would be to our mutual advantage if one of us was known to be incapable of acting in any way other than the way that would involve compliance with the strategy favoring him. Paradoxically, sometimes incorrigible obstinacy enables agreement, co-ordination and compromise. For it would advantage us to agree to abide by the arbitrary policy one of us has so as to avoid the overhead costs and coercions of Leviathans. Our private commitment need not consist in accepting a state; for there need be no exogenous penalty for defection, nor any additional cost to the solution. 21 Of course, had we each a policy bias we could make no progress: who should (could?) concede? But this brings me to the other thing. To present Leviathan solutions with a problem truly parallel to the one we posed for Gauthier, we must imagine there being two (or two possible) Leviathans, one, known to enforce confession, the other, non-confession. It is mutually advantageous for us to each commit to the same Leviathan, but which? It is not uniquely rational for us to both make a Hobbesian side-bet with either; each of us would favor joint alliance with a different Leviathan. Indeed, before we can rationally co-ordinate on a choice, we still need a joint randomizer to choose. Hopefully a third Leviathan would randomize to decide which policy to enforce, in which case our individual expected utilities would be highest allying with him compared to SMing. (Each of us would prefer us to ally with the Leviathan whose policy is known to favor us, but neither of us can rationally expect the other to accept this over gambling with the randomizing Leviathan.) So even if Gauthier can't give a co-operative solution here (because of the unavailability of a joint randomizer), neither could Hobbes give his political one. This proves that recourse to an authoritative lottery need not be recourse to a state. For in attempting a Hobbesian solution to some PDs in nature, we must use an agreed-to-be- authoritative joint randomizer to launch it. We cannot rationally decide to which Leviathan to commit without one, or unless one of Them has one. And what makes one randomizer authoritative is not that a Leviathan enforces the results of His randomizer, but that we rationally acquiesce in taking His to be authoritative. Thus the randomizer is a device for getting from nature to a state. It must thus be available in nature, not only as an alternative to the decision-making processes available in nature. 22 Thus the requisites for rational joint alliance to a Leviathan resemble those for rational joint commitment to a strategy for further voluntary choices. At least one of two possible requisites must be available. One is that of a joint randomizer. The Leviathan must be disposed to use one to decide His policy if we are to rationally ally with Him; the 9 contracting agents must use one to implement joint strategies for further choices. If one is unavailable, the requisite is that there be only one available mutually advantageous policy--the Leviathan must have (a secret) one; or, in a Gauthier solution, exactly one of the agents must have one (one which he cannot but insist on, forcing the other agent's acquiescence). This is unsurprising, for Gauthier's solution to PDs was to be like Hobbes' in two ways: First, the agents each choose it for individual advantage. Second, when the agents severally choose it, optimality is the by-product. But Gauthier's solution needs no coercive and costly enforcement. It can offer moral (and rationally attractive) solutions to more conflicts than could Hobbes', for in being cheaper it will more frequently surpass individual strategies in expected utility. But there are deeper problems here.... IV The Rational Unsolvability of Co-ordination Problems in Mixed Joint Strategies; Reflections On Luck There is a deep issue near the first two cases, most clearly near the second: Is it always in principle possible for agents to rationally adopt a lottery whenever one is needed to implement any rational joint strategy? I have so far treated these cases as unproblematic because it seemed obvious Gauthier's principles would naturally direct agents to lottery solutions to CPs, and that only some unfounded stipulation would make that option unavailable. But if there are systematic difficulties with adopting lottery solutions, these cases become surprising counter-examples to the scope of Gauthier's claims concerning the rationality of co-operation in PDs. Moreover, if this does not plague Hobbesian solutions, Gauthier would have failed to offer a lower-cost alternative to all of them. This worry is not much developed in the literature. While it is unclear exactly how authoritative joint randomization is to be undertaken, it is often assumed that it can, perhaps, be done by the agents' mutual fiat. But I will now argue that it cannot always be done in this or any way. Ideal PD agents would see the advantage in deciding their choices by a joint lottery; also in jointly baptizing one of the many possible lottery methods as authoritative if none are already forced on them by a state or by there being but one lottery method available in nature (in which case they would so baptize it); also that if several methods are available, it would optimize for them both to commit to one; also for someone to run it. Still, some vital questions remain unanswered 23 : If several lottery methods are available in nature, how are agents to rationally and jointly choose one as authoritative, and to decide who shall run it? The rational mandate to use one does not say which one to use, nor who should run it. If these problems have no determinate solution the co-operative strategy cannot be (rationally) implemented, and, where only a joint mixed strategy beats individual SMing (as in Case 2), no co-operative solution is possible. I see no way to solve these problems in the standard conception of rationality. Should we flip a coin to decide which randomizing process to use as authoritative (e.g., a further coin-toss, or some natural, random phenomenon), then flip again to decide who shall run it? But this initiates a vicious regress since presumably we need yet more lotteries to decide which one shall determine the authoritative one and which to use in determining who shall run the one for determining who shall run the authoritative one, etc. Hopeless. 10 Maybe one of us should just volunteer. Fine, but who? It doesn't matter. Then how are we to decide? Just do it. What if we both propose to just do it? One must yield. Who? It doesn't matter. Right, so who? OK, the agents should take the first available method; the agent closest to it should run it. But why? And what if two methods turn up simultaneously, or if the agents are equi-distant to the single method, etc.? 24 If we are lucky, only one process will be available (or the others will be costlier), and only one of us will be able to run it (or the cost of the other doing so will be prohibitive). Since it would optimize for one process to be run by one of us, and since there is only one possible (or cost-effective) process and one possible (or cost-effective) operator, it would maximize for him to operate it: For he cannot have the benefits of co-operation unless he does so, while by doing so, he can unilaterally save himself from mutual defection (this incidentally benefitting his partner). That is, it would maximize for him to unilaterally commit to the strategy of implementing the lottery process necessary to implementing the joint strategy (providing this is not more costly than his benefits in having it implemented). And it would maximize for the other agent to conditionally acknowledge this lottery as authoritative, and to conditionally commit to complying with it. We might reflect here that while this problem is vexing, requiring the non-rational good fortune of a paucity of methods of co-ordination to facilitate implementation of the co-operative strategy, that we now face this problem betokens tremendous progress: We have reduced a PD to a mere CP. We now see the advantage in co-ordinating and no longer see ourselves as conflicted. But there is still the CP, every reason to think some CPs are rationally intractable. For while we do not care which lottery method we use (if they are costless or equally costful), nor who runs it (if that is costless or equally costful for both of us), this is just what makes it impossible for us to rationally choose here; and baring happy accidents limiting our options to one, it seems we cannot (rationally) resolve these difficulties. We will then, wherever an optimal joint pure strategy is also unavailable (e.g., in Case 2), be unable to co-operate. 25 IV.1 Rationality and Equal Options What prevents a solution is that the agents' indifference between methods means they can't choose one. But doesn't this presuppose that an agent cannot rationally choose between A and B unless he prefers one to the other; that two agents cannot jointly choose between A and B unless both prefer the same? But surely in choosing between good A or good B and bad C, an agent who prefers A or B to C and who chooses A or chooses B-- no matter how--chooses rationally. He is rational if he chooses A over C, or B over C, and is at worst non-rational, not irrational, in choosing A over B or B over A. So an action is rational if there is at least one true description of it on which it is prima face rational (or better, at least one partitioning of options where a choice between them is rational), as here. Further, since nearly every possible action must contain components from options between which the agent is preference-indifferent (e.g., the exact shape of the letters he uses in signing a check), beings capable of ordinary actions must have things like deterministic or randomizing choice tendencies to "fill in the details" of rationally preferred actions and enabling choices between equal options. 26 So it would be 11 absurd to call an action irrational simply because, perforce, it involves non-rational choices in its details. So "choosing" a lottery method is not irrational just for involving these. But can someone be said to choose an option he does not prefer over all others? For then he doesn't choose it in the sense that it comes to be his by a preference that only it be his. It just somehow comes to affect his behavior or utility, which seems to be something that merely happens, not that he makes happen. But let us be liberal: an individual has chosen an option just if (1) it affects his subsequent behavior (or utility) because he preferred it over all others (i.e., it is "preference rational"), or (2) it does so partly because he preferred it or other options over some he dispreferred and partly because of some non-rational process (i.e., it is "process rational"). Thus a rational action is not just a preference-expressing or satisfaction-maximizing one. Rationality is dirtier: to maximize one must often first, or componently, be able to choose among equal options. Rational choices are constrained but not fully determined by preferences and beliefs. But does granting any of this about rational agents make any difference to whether they can co-ordinate out of nature? Suppose it would advantage two such agents to co- ordinate their choices by any of many available further methods of joint choice, but that each is indifferent about which to use. Can they always in principle choose one? Obviously not by mere preference. Can they with their several individual further choice processes? Only on one of four conditions: (i) By co-incidence these processes are the same in kind and so would always choose the same options. (ii) While they are different, one always automatically acquiesces in the other's choice, the other always actively chooses; their processes are complementary. (iii) By a chain of choices involving individual processes and preferences (e.g., a series of "binary sorts"), their further processes could be made the same or (iv) complementary, for any case. Conditions (iii) and (iv) are just special cases of (i) and (ii) respectively, and (ii) is functionally just a special case of (i). There are only two possible ways for (i) to be implemented: by deterministic or randomizing processes of further choice. Suppose both agents have deterministic ones. They may try to agree on which lottery method to use in choosing their actions in a PD by individually applying their processes in a series of binary choices between all available methods. Assume there are finitely many. Assume each agent arrives at a single method. If they still differ they need only agree on which of the two remaining ones to use. Now their individual processes, in individually choosing among these two, will either choose the same method or not. If the same, they can use it to solve their CP; if not, they cannot solve it. Since the former is not guaranteed, they may be unable to solve it. Consider now agents each with randomizing processes of further choice. They individually choose as before, each arriving at a method. Now they only need agree on one of these if they still differ. Can they? If they each have a randomizing process that selects a given option in a choice between two with a 50% probability (though any non- zero probability would be helpful), then on their first attempt at agreeing, they have a 25% chance of succeeding. (Success is each of their processes voting yes for a method; thus on any try, there are 4 possibilities, yes/yes, yes/no, no/no, no/yes, the chances of yes/yes, 1/4.) By every successive attempt they have an ever higher chance of having 12 agreed. Were this series finitely convergent, they would be guaranteed to agree in finite time (if each try takes only finite time). Unfortunately, the series only asymptotically approaches unity. So while they are guaranteed consensus in infinite time, there is no guarantee they can solve their CP by any given time. Since every possible choice process is one of these two, and since neither is guaranteed to solve their CP in finite time (all that they ever have), no method is guaranteed. Since they could only rationally co-ordinate if they could solve their problem, and they may not be able to, rationality cannot itself always assure co- ordination in a PD. Nor therefore can it, by itself, always there rationalize co-operation. Co-ordination between the agents is possible only should they be lucky enough to have co-ordination-facilitating processes lucky enough to solve their CP in the given time. So whether they can rationally co-ordinate and co-operate depends on luck; on something beyond the agents' rational choice as defined by their individual preferences or choice processes. So even granting that an option can be rationally individually chosen where it could not be preference-chosen over equal options (and even if a joint choice is rational if it results from individually process rational choices), it still does not follow that rational agents in nature can always co-ordinate by fiat. No matter how rational they are, nor how willing to co-operate, they will not always co-operate in all possible PDs where the only obstacle is their agreeing on a co-ordinating device. 27 But suppose we insisted that truly rational communities could always resolve such CPs (--for wouldn't we think a community was crazy if its members just left crucial issues hanging because they couldn't overcome such "trivial" obstacles to agreement on how to act?; and isn't it the business of rational choice theory to recover from our pre- critical judgments about what is rational and what isn't, some generalized principles summarizing and explicating our pre-critical "intuitions"?) 28 : Then we've just proved that the rationality of a community (i.e., the ability of the members of the community to coordinate in ways they believe likely to achieve agreed goals) is not the sum contribution of its members conceived as merely preference-rational, nor as also process- rational. It requires a further lucky natural suitedness to co-ordination among their processes. We can put this implication in another way. Suppose that strategic rationality concerns choices where outcomes depend on the choices and/or choice bases of other agents, parametric rationality, choices where outcomes depend only on natural conditions and the choices and/or choice bases of the individual chooser. Then we have shown that the strategic rationalities of agents in a community of choosers differ from parametric in demanding not only choice processes, but also luck in them being suited-to-co-ordination with the individuals in the community. That is, two or more agents are not strategically rational in their dealings with each other unless their several choice processes luckily suit them to co-ordination with each other. IV.2 Leviathans Suppose it is to our advantage to co-ordinate, but that we happen not to be endowed with suitable co-ordination-facilitating processes. Would a Leviathan help? No. Hobbes thought a Leviathan could be established in either of two ways, by "institution" or by 13 "acquisition." 29 In the former, the Leviathan comes to exist by agents in nature creating one to escape the vicissitudes of nature: it is supposedly rational for a given agent to ally with a Leviathan if all others are prepared to do so as well. The agents have as their only incentive to so ally that their joint commitment would remove them from nature and place them under the Leviathan's protection, freeing them from the war of all against all. The only penalty for not signing up is the continuing nastiness of the alternative--life in the state of nature. There are no further individual signing bonuses, nor further individual penalties for not signing. After they signed up there were rewards and threats aplenty from the Leviathan to enforce His policies, but that's different. Now, unfortunately, establishment of a Leviathan by institution involves co-ordination. And if the agents were not guaranteed of being able to co-ordinate on a lottery, then they are not on a Leviathan either. For they must agree on who He shall be, and on what policies He will have. And it was just their inability to agree on policies which required them to resort to a lottery in Case 2, their hypothesized inability to co-ordinate on which lottery to use that drove us to consider whether a Leviathan could help. But as we've seen, we may be unable to rationally agree on joint alliance to a single Leviathan because unable to agree on which policy He should enforce. While if we propose to institute a randomizing Leviathan, we have still to choose among equally attractive possible Leviathans with different equally attractive lotteries; and we could not rationally ally with either if we could not co- ordinate in general in choices between equal options. It is surprising how long this problem has gone unacknowledged in the literature. Consider a recent book-length treatment of Hobbes's solution to such problems. Jean Hampton 30 , recognizing that agents in nature face the problem of selecting a Leader, a Leviathan, suggests that that problem can be solved using one of the following methods: a) One of the agents could impose additional costs on the other should he refuse to accept the Leviathan the first prefers. But what if, as I stipulate, the agents have equal powers to impose costs, so that either or neither can make the other's refusing to concede so expensive as to induce the other to capitulate? Then either both will be willing to capitulate and they will have their problem back in deciding whose capitulation shall stand, or neither will capitulate, and again, their problem returns. b) One of the agents can hold out until the other gives in. But what is to prevent both from holding out? And what is to suddenly make it rational for (just) one to give in? c) Since each has a stake in some resolution being attained, each has an incentive to concede to the other's preferences. But since both have this incentive, both should be prepared to concede; how are they to decide whose gracious concession to accept? d) Since the problem becomes more urgent as a deadline for a solution approaches, one agent should concede as it approaches. But while the approach of the deadline makes things more urgent, given that the agents have equal stakes in their preferred solutions, who should rationally cave in? e) The game is like a game of chicken, and at the last second, both should deviate from the deadlock. But how are the agents rationally to decide who, as it were, shall veer left, and who right?; what in rationality can say who should concede and who should hold? f) One of the agents should yield to the other's irrational inflexibility. But what if both agents are perfectly rational?; what if neither is particularly inflexible? g) One of the agents might have a greater stake in achieving a resolution, and so should, rationally, be more willing 14 to concede. Sure, but what if they have equal stakes, as, I stipulate, is the case here? h) The more risk averse agent should cave in. But what if, as I stipulate, the agents are equally risk averse? i) The agents should use a symmetry-breaking technique, like flipping a coin. Right, but what if they each have a coin, etc., as I stipulate here? How are they rationally (or even by fiat) to decide which of several equally attractive symmetry- breaking methods to use? This just returns us to our original problem. 31 j) The agents could vote on a solution. But when the problem holds between two agents, as here, a vote may not settle the question; voting is like them each choosing a joint lottery method by their several further choice processes, and there is no guarantee of the agents being able to reach a consensus on the joint lottery method in a finite time using these processes. Even with all of this flailing about, then, there is, I insist, no guarantee that the agents can rationally solve their co-ordination problem in attempting to institute a Leviathan. All of these proposals depend on contingencies in the provision of which lady luck might not have obliged. But couldn't a Leviathan solve our problem for us by imposing Himself on us, forcing us to so ally, and so resolving our CP on choosing a method of choosing a solution? This involves the other way for a Leviathan to be established, vis., when one acquires the loyalty of a subject by conquest. It is "be loyal or else." Since people can be "conquered" by positive as well as negative reward, perhaps "if you're loyal I'll give you this" would also count as establishment by acquisition. Now I have three points to make about this. First, nothing guarantees it to happen. Hampton 32 assumed that where there were several candidate Leviathans, one will be the strongest, and the agents, to avoid the harms of this Leviathan and to protect themselves from other, weaker Leviathans, and from each other, would ally with it. But what if there are equally strong incentive-or threat-offering competitor candidate Sovereigns? How are the agents to pick? Discussing this, Hampton assumes 33 that one confederacy (Leviathan) will win out in the "market" of confederacies as the strongest one, making it the one with which the agents ought rationally to ally. But what ensures this? Why might there not, again, prove to be two equals? Again, considering this scenario 34 , Hampton claims that the agents coming to have a Leviathan by acquisition is really the agents making self- interested choices, co-ordinating by means of a salient. They want a Ruler, both want to have the same Ruler, whichever one they end up with, and both are happy to have one chosen for them by that Ruler offering the strongest incentive to alliance; that Ruler's incentive makes Him a natural "salient." (Thus she seems to think that a Leviathan by acquisition reduces to a Leviathan by institution.) Fine, but now recall our old problem. Suppose there are two candidate Rulers, offering equal incentives; who do we want to conquer us? Suppose either of these Rulers would become strongest if we both allied with him, but each is equally attractive for each of us, or each of us mildly favors a different one: how are we supposed to solve our problem? Contra Hampton 35 , it seems that nothing will inevitably lead to one Ruler's having a monopoly on ultimate power, and so there is nothing to inevitably make one Ruler naturally "salient," the one with which it would be rational for both agents to ally. Hampton seems wrong in saying that "nothing is required for the sovereign's institution that these self-interested people are unable to perform." 36 In fact, there may be nothing they can do to make any candidate Leviathan the one with 15 which it is rational for both agents to ally. My second point on Leviathans by acquisition: Some of the ways Leviathans acquire subjects do not happen by the agents' co-ordinating. Rather, agents individually ally with the Leviathan to escape an individual penalty or to attain an individual reward. They pursue individual, not joint strategies. My third point: In those ways in which acquisition does happen by the agents' co- ordinating, it does not happen by them co-ordinating in a way that can count as them having solved their original choice problem. The situation may be one involving co- ordination of some form, as where the Leviathan's threats and seductions induce co- ordination ("You must both comply with my wishes; if either of you does not, you both shall be punished/neither rewarded"). Here, the agents solve a problem by rationally co- ordinating, but not their original one, only the new one of how to escape the wrath (or earn the rewards) of Leviathan. None of this is a "solution" to the original choice problem because it involves exogenous factors, ones external to both the original scenario and its pay-off structure. The Leviathan changes the problem into one in which there is a unique best equilibrium, so that the agents no longer solve their problem by a selection by mutually agreed fiat from among a plurality of good equilibria--there is no longer such a plurality to select from. The agents have not solved their problem; rather, an external force has come in and changed their situation so that they no longer have it. This can of course happen, but it is not a rational solution to a partial conflict as such, since it removes the conflict. To summarize then, a Leviathan by acquisition is not guaranteed to present itself, and even if it does, opting for it is not a solution to the original choice problem (but to a new one). While a Leviathan by institution is no more guaranteed to work as a strategy of solution than attempting to resort to a joint lottery. Unsurprising, for the device of an instituted Leviathan was invented to solve a different problem than that of agreement on a co-ordinated pattern of behavior, vis., "how can it be rational to comply with such agreements?", not "which agreement (on how exactly to co-ordinate) is it rational to make?" 37 Agents unlucky enough to be insufficiently endowed as to be able to co-ordinate can only escape (not solve) their problem by the intrusion of an exogenous factor. Whether a genuinely co-operative solution is possible in a given circumstance of justice (or whether something is such a circumstance) depends in part on sheer luck (in us being co- ordination suited); and we can't overcome bad luck by reason alone. This reduces the number of circumstances admitting of a Gauthian resolution. In effect, morality (and the solvability of a co-ordination problem) depends on luck in the very operation of rationality. (This is a systematic problem. Of course we must also be lucky enough not to be blown up by a volcano in the meanwhile.) Ironically, reasoning our way out of partial conflict through rationally instituted moral or political artifices, systematically depends on non-rational accidents. But it would be wrong to think that wherever a Gauthian resolution must fail, the Hobbesian solution of mutual rational alliance to a state can succeed. For we saw that rationality may be unable to institute a Leviathan to extract us through rational commitments from the worst circumstances of indecision. A solution could only arise 16 non-rationally (relative to the original circumstances of choice) from natural accidents (suiting us to co-ordination); or an escape (not a solution as such) could be afforded by the intrusion of a (single) conqueror with his own agenda. Thus that venerated artifice, the Hobbesian state, once presumed to attract our rational allegiance as our last recourse from the war of all against all, must often be a purely natural object, one in principle not rationally institutable by its prospective constituency; it must have its own agenda. We nearly always have many methods and agents of randomization. Since our rationality affords no a priori guarantee that we can always in principle rationally jointly choose among them, how do we so frequently manage to co-ordinate and co-operate? Evolution would favor communities of agents either genetically endowed with convergent tie-breaking processes, or who were not preference-indifferent and who shared preferences on these matters (or who were, happily enough, subject to certain kinds of conquest). Evolution favors the prejudiced and the picky (and sometimes the conquered), both in individuals, and, especially, in communities. For such communities could solve CPs to their advantage, while others would be stuck with sub-optimal individual strategies. Our present co-operative practices, then, are the beneficiaries of the evolutionary tendency to produce individuals suited-to-co-ordination. But as we saw, the possibility of co-ordination, and so of co-operation, cannot be guaranteed by the individual rationality of agents. It is an unwitting grace of forces themselves of necessity non-rational. Conclusions We can now see that some common precepts of contractarian moral rationalism are false. That a rational choice is a unique function of an agent's preferences given his beliefs was falsified by the fact that an agent can face a choice among equal options. If he can rationally choose among them, rationality must merely be constrained, not exhausted by, the expression of preferences and beliefs; there must also be what I called process rationality, not just preference rationality. That the rationality of collective action (i.e., of groups of individuals co-ordinatively interacting to attain agreed goals) is a unique function of the rationalities of the individuals comprising the collectivity was disproved for both individual preference and process rationality. For were individual rationality merely preference rationality, then just as individuals can face impossible choices among equal options, so can groups of individuals; a group can be indifferent among options even where it prefers at least one of them to some inferiors. And even supplementing individual preference rationality with process rationality so that agents can break preference ties in their individual choices, groups can still face inco-ordinable choices among options process equal for all individuals. The processes individuals use to break ties may not combine to allow groups of individuals to do so. If we hold that groups can always make rational such choices, we must understand the rationality of a collectivity not just as the expression of the preference rationality of its individual members, but as that plus their process rationality, plus a further constraint on the latter to suit the individuals for co-ordination. Moreover, since nothing guarantees that any set of individuals will have several choice processes 17 jointly sufficient to enable agreement on how to break ties in collectively designing such processes, this suitedness to co-ordination cannot itself always be something designable by the group. Rather, it must sometimes be in some way non-rational and adventitious. These reflections on individual and group rationality suggest that to understand strategic rationality (the rationality of agents in interactions with other agents aiming at outcomes which depend on the choices of several agents), we must take groups as our unit of analysis, not individuals; individual strategic rationality must be understood as an irreducible relation (of suitedness to co-ordination) between the individual and her environing group, not as a trait of an individual considered separately. Our reflections also suggest that to understand the rationality of a group (i.e., the ability of its members to co-ordinate in attaining agreed goals), we must invoke invoke evolutionary forces, ones bearing on the group and so on individuals in their relations to their group. We cannot suppose the group's rationality to consist simply in the sum of the preference and process rationality of its members taken separately. Further, since we must understand the strategic rationality of an individual in relation to her environing group, our analysis may suggest that whether someone is strategically rational depends on what group she is in. An agent may have processes of choice suiting her for co-ordination in one group, but not in another. So whether she is strategically rational may be relative to what group she is in. But we might go even further: Suppose we thought that for any two people (regardless of their native group), the two of them are only strategically rational if, in possible dealings with each other, they could always co- ordinate in the kinds of situations we have considered. Then it is a condition on any agent's being strategically rational that all beings which can count as agents are luckily such that their choice processes suit them to co-ordination. 38 That optimal resolutions of partial conflicts are always achievable by rational mutual compromise was disproved by the fact that the stubborness of one agent where agents must choose between otherwise equal options may be the only thing allowing them to solve their CPs. The rest must defer to he who cannot yield, his inflexibility useful in eliminating otherwise equally attractive options. That the state can be understood at least hypothetically as a wholly designed object chosen by its subjects was disproved by the fact that there may be two equal Leviathans so that, since the group could not preference or process rationally choose between them, the only way it could have come to be ruled by one is if it imposed itself. That a just--welfare optimizing--state, must be choosable by a community, fell with the fourth dogma: there could be an optimizing state a group could not rationally choose. And finally, that any maximally just state must be one to which all its citizens would hypothetically commit in individually rational contracts was disproved by the fact that several states could offer optimality, and individuals as rational contractors might not, therefore, rationally be able to contract for even one of them. 18 Notes 1. I began thinking about the issues discussed here when I was the commentator on a paper Jordan Howard Sobel presented at the 1989 meetings of the Canadian Philosophical Association. A descendent of his paper has appeared: "Constrained Maximization," Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 21 (1991), pp. 25-52. For helpful comments made variously on my commentary and on a draft of the present work read at Dalhousie University, my thanks especially to Sobel (who gave me written comments) and also to John Baker, Nathan Brett, Steven Burns, Richmond Campbell, Bob Martin, Jan Narveson, Sue Sherwin, Terry Tomkow, Jane van Arscotte, Peter Valentine, Kadri Vihvelin, Michael Webster and Sheldon Wein. Thanks also to the anonymous reader for this Journal for many helpful suggestions. 2. Sobel, "Constrained Maximization." 3. Sobel, "Constrained Maximization," pp. 25, 37, 40, 42. 4. I here develop possibilities Sobel negatively reviews in passing. See Sobel, "Constrained Maximization," pp. 28, 29-30, 48, 50. 5. Parts of the next five paragraphs are loosely adapted from my `Preference's Progress: Rational Self-Alteration and the Rationality of Morality,' Dialogue, 30 (1991), pp. 4-5. 6. Little hangs on the details of minimax relative concession here, but briefly: If we each invest equally in an enterprise, then, ceteris paribus, we should profit as much and as near to equally as possible in the circumstances. 7. David Gauthier, Morals By Agreement (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1986), p. 167. 8. Gauthier, Morals By Agreement, p. 168. 9. David Gauthier, "Moral Artifice", Canadian Journal of Philosophy 18 (1988), p. 389. 10. Sobel, "Constrained Maximization." 11. This is a version of an example of Sobel's (Sobel, "Constrained Maximization," p. 28), in turn adapted from Gauthier. 12. David Gauthier, Morals By Agreement, p. 120. 13. Sobel, "Constrained Maximization," pp. 29-30. 14. Sobel, "Constrained Maximization," pp. 28, 30, 33. 19 15. As Sobel does in more careful and technical terms, in his "Constrained Maximization," p. 27. 16. Sobel, "Constrained Maximization," pp. 34-37. 17. Jan Narveson suggested the individual randomizer. I am not sure whether he meant that the agent should pursue an individual strategy of individual randomization, or that each agent should provisionally commit to a joint strategy involving each agent's agreeing to the individual use of individual randomizers. I presume the second, where each agent only randomizes provided the other conditionally disposes himself to do so too, for the first is irrational. If I randomized, while you straightforwardly maximized, that would have you always confessing but me not confessing half the time, so I would be getting suckered half the time. 18. Perhaps the outcome utility of mutual defection is then the minimax: for neither agent would rationally accept less, nor could he rationally expect more. 19. Sobel, "Constrained Maximization," pp. 38-43. I've simplified his case a bit. 20. Compare with Gregory S. Kavka, Hobbesian Moral and Political Theory (Princeton University Press: Princeton, New Jersey, 1986), pp. 182-188, especially pp. 186-187. 21. For that matter one of us might just happen to have a fair randomizer. And it would then advantage each of us for us each to duly conditionally commit to taking it for the authoritative one and to complying with its dictates, again saving ourselves the overhead costs and coercions of the Leviathan. 22. Except in the sense that from an unconstrained situation, we can rationally move to mutually agreed constraint by agreeing to refer the choice problem to an agreed joint lottery, not to be confused with an agreed coercive force. 23. I became aware of these questions through Sobel, though he does not put the problem in quite these terms. 24. The reader for this Journal offered the following illustrative example and commentary: Two people need to go through a narrow doorway. One must go before the other, it doesn't matter which one. So who should go? They can easily communicate. One says: "After you," but simultaneously the other is saying "After you." At this point both start going through the doorway. This is clearly unsatisfactory. So they both stop. Then each says "I'll go first." One can see that in principle this could go on forever with them never getting through the doorway, though no irrationality is in evidence...even when communication is possible and an explicit agreement can 20 be made, rational agents will not always be able to make such an agreement. Exactly. A more detailed proof follows in the next section. 25. Gauthier agrees that where there is more than one best equilibrium, "coordination is a matter of chance, not of reason." (David Gauthier, "Coordination," Dialogue 14 (1975), pp. 195-221.) But he thinks that "the salience of one of these equilibria...may be used to reconceive the situation as having but one best equilibrium." Successful coordination is possible if "all the persons involved in the situation apprehend the same outcome as salient." (p. 213) Perhaps, though Margaret Gilbert in her "Rationality and Salience," Philosophical Studies 57 (1989), pp. 61-77, argues that unless one of these options being salient alters the pay-off structure in utilities of the choices, however good for both agents it would be if both chose by the salient, this does not give either agent an individual reason to choose by it, even if, as a matter of contingent psychology, and independent of pure rationality, agents might both tend to choose by it (pp. 71-73). In any case, if we stipulate, as I here do, that there is no salient for one of these options, or if several are equally salient, Gauthier will acknowledge that "coordination is a matter of chance, not of reason." And he admits there is no guarantee of a unique salient ("Coordination," p. 211). He does not seem to have fully traced out the limitations this may imply on the universality of rational co-operation in PDs, and in both "Coordination" and Morals By Agreement, he has been more interested in cases where there are salients, where, by his lights, coordination by a salient is possible. This interest in how coordination can be facilitated by salients when they are available explains, I think, why the possibility that CPs like those we are considering, in the conditions we are imagining, are irresolvable, has received little attention. It is widely assumed that solving perfect information CPs is trivial, and many philosophers tend to advance incautious generalizations which imply the solvability (by pure rationality) of all such CPs. Thus one finds Jean Hampton in her Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition (Cambridge University Press: Cambridge, 1986) saying of agents facing a CP in choosing a Sovereign that, "nothing is required for the sovereign's institution that [rational]... self-interested people are unable to perform." (p. 172) And we have David Lewis saying in his Convention (Harvard University Press: Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1969): In considering how to solve coordination problems, I have post-poned the answer that first comes to mind: by agreement. If the agents can communicate...they can ensure a common understanding of their problem by discussing it. They can choose a coordination equilibrium--an arbitrary one, or one especially good for some or all of them....Coordination by means of an agreement is not, of course, an alternative to coordination by means of concordant mutual expectations. Rather, agreement is one means of producing those expectations. (pp. 33-34) But it is not clear how the agreement can be arrived at in the first place. This problem receives elaboration in our next section. (I suggest above and below that luck is required to solve certain co-ordination problems. Lewis, too, discusses how luck can start 21 conventions, but he does not invoke it as a possible requirement for making arbitrary face-to-face agreements.) 26. Sobel suggests (in his "Constrained Maximization," pp. 28-29), in another connection, that a rational agent can be imagined to have the power to randomize "in his head," and to commit to acting in a way determined by that process. 27. I thank Nathan Brett, Steven Burns, and especially, Kadri Vihvelin and Sheldon Wein for discussion on these points. 28. My thanks to the reader for this Journal for pressing me on why we can just "insist" in this way. 29. Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, C.B. MacPherson, ed., (Penguin Books: Harmondsworth, Middlesex, England, 1968), pp. 228-239, 251-257. 30. Hampton, Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition, pp. 155-160. 31. Kavka too thinks the agents can just "flip a coin." (Kavka Hobbesian Moral and Political Theory, pp. 185-186.) Well sure, if they could agree on which coin to flip, and on who is to make the toss. 32. Hampton, Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition, pp. 167-168. 33. Hampton, Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition, p. 169. 34. Hampton, Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition, pp. 168-172. 35. Hampton, Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition, p. 172. 36. Hampton, Hobbes and the Social Contract Tradition, p. 172. 37. Or at any rate, such is the part of Hobbes in which Gauthier is primarily interested. Actually, apparently Hobbes wanted the Leviathan not only to enforce compliance with laws (with ideal co-ordinated patterns of choice), but to resolve disagreements about which laws there should be. Communities of agents might not be able to agree on laws because their members might have different stakes in different possible laws, but the Leviathan could choose laws by the standard of which ones would be in His individual self-interest; He would not face a conflictual CP with Himself. (But, contra Hampton and Hobbes, there is no guarantee that He can decide even though He need only cater to His self-interest. For His self-interest requires Him not to provoke revolution, which means He must please His constituency; and if it is divided, any choice of His will displease some of its members, perhaps enough to over-throw him.) However if agents cannot agree on laws, then they cannot agree on a Ruler if that involves agreeing on which kind of Ruler He shall be, i.e., on which laws He will enforce. But suppose the agents, 22 realizing it is better for all that there be some laws, decide to refer this to a Leviathan; they try to choose a Leviathan not knowing what laws He will favor, or try to choose one whom they know will decide the laws by a randomizer: Now they still face the problem of co-ordinating on which of two possible inscrutable or randomizing Leviathans to choose. So the use of Leviathans may not solve the problem of which laws to have, since we still have the problem of deciding which law-maker to have. 38. Thanks to Sue Sherwin for provoking this line of thought. work_clhwaebarrcotpczo5d6yjabx4 ---- S0031819119000482jra 63..91 Power, Predistribution, and Social Justice MARTIN O’NEILL Abstract The idea of predistribution has the potential to offer a valuable and distinctive ap- proach to political philosophers, political scientists, and economists, in thinking about social justice and the creation of more egalitarian economies. It is also an idea that has drawn the interest of politicians of the left and centre-left, promising an alternative to traditional forms of social democracy. But the idea of predistribution is not well understood, and stands in need of elucidation. This article explores ways of drawing the conceptual and normative distinction between predistribution and redis- tribution, examining those general categories when considering the roles of public services and fiscal transfers, and looking at the ways in which government policies can empower and disempower different individuals and groups within the economy. This article argues that the most initially plausible and common-sensical ways of drawing the distinction between predistributive and redistributive public policies collapse when put under analytical pressure. It concludes that the distinction between predistribution and redistribution is best seen in terms of the aims or effects of policies rather than a deeper division of policy types, and argues that, once seen in those terms, predistribution is a central concern of social justice. 1. Introduction: Predistribution, Redistribution, and Social Justice In recent years the idea of ‘predistribution’ has received a good deal of attention, both in academic discussions of inequality and social justice, and within the world of practical politics. And yet this idea of predistribution is not always used clearly, and much needs to be done to put the notion on a more secure footing. This essay aims to uncover, and then eradicate, various confusions about the idea of pre- distribution, putting the idea on a firmer footing, and thereby clear- ing the way for more productive future discussions of policies and institutions for addressing economic inequality. When political philosophers think about egalitarian public policy, and about what states need to do in order to deliver social and eco- nomic justice, their attention has most often naturally been drawn to questions of redistribution. They typically consider how states can create more equal outcomes through standard fiscal mechanisms, 63 doi:10.1017/S0031819119000482 © The Royal Institute of Philosophy, 2019 First published online 13 November 2019 Philosophy 95 2020 Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core as when more advantaged members of society are taxed by the state, which then uses those fiscal flows to fund transfer payments and to provide public services. It is illustrative here that, when G. A. Cohen launched his powerful and influential critique of Rawls’s account of social justice, the totemic practical issue on which he focussed was the level of the top marginal rate of income taxation.1 While this predominant concern with questions of redistribution as being central to thinking about justice and equality generally still remains, it is noteworthy that more recent work in political philoso- phy increasingly brings questions of predistribution to the fore. As T. M. Scanlon puts it in his 2018 book Why Does Inequality Matter?, ‘[a]nother way of promoting equality, or avoiding inequal- ity, is through what has been called predistribution, that is to say, through the laws and policies that determine individuals’ pretax incomes’.2 This shift of attention to the broader set of laws and pol- icies that produce inequality aligns with a general broadening of concern with the normative assessment of a range of socioeconomic institutions, and away from an artificially circumscribed focus on only a particular subset of the ways in which institutions can either foster or reduce economic inequality.3 This broader focus could en- compass, for example, concerns with minimum wage levels, or the regulation of trade unions and wage bargaining processes, as well as issues of financial and corporate regulation, the regulation of import- ant sectors such as the housing or energy markets, and the use of na- tional and local government procurement spending in shaping the structure of markets.4 1 G. A. Cohen, ‘Incentives, Inequality and Community’, Tanner Lectures on Human Values (Salt Lake City, 1991), 261–329, e.g. 263–4; G. A Cohen, Rescuing Justice and Equality, (Harvard University Press, 2008), e.g. 27–86. 2 T. M. Scanlon, Why Does Inequality Matter? (Oxford University Press, 2018), 102. 3 See Martin O’Neill and Thad Williamson, ‘The Promise of Predistribution’, Policy Network, 2012; Nick Pearce, ‘What Should Social Democrats Believe?’, Juncture 20.2 (2013), 101–110; Alan Thomas, Republic of Equals: Predistribution and Property-Owning Democracy, (Oxford University Press, 2017). 4 Emily McTernan, Martin O’Neill, Christian Schemmel, and Fabian Schuppert, ‘If You Care About Social Equality You Want a Big State: Home, Work, Care and Social Egalitarianism’, Juncture, 23.2 (2016), 138–44; Joe Guinan and Martin O’Neill, ‘The Institutional Turn: Labour’s New Political Economy’, Renewal: a Journal of Social 64 Martin O’Neill Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core A similar broadening of concern can be seen in recent work by leading economists, with Joseph Stiglitz also using the language of predistribution to describe his 2016 proposals for ‘Rewriting the Rules of the American Economy’.5 As Stiglitz puts it in his 2019 book, People, Power and Profits: Progressive Capitalism for an Age of Discontent, ‘If we succeed in making market incomes more equal, there is less of a burden on redistribution. This emphasis on pre-dis- tribution is important. It highlights that getting a fairer distribution of income is not just a matter of redistribution, of taxing the rich to give to the more needy’.6 The idea here seems to be a straightforward one, at least at first acquaintance: predistribution is about the role of government in changing market outcomes, and thereby creating fairer distributive outcomes without the need for directly engaging in redistribution.7 Thomas Piketty, meanwhile, has stressed the need to pursue redistribution and predistribution in combination, with the two being ‘complementary, not substitutes,’8 while also Democracy, 26.2, 2018, 5–16; Joe Guinan and Martin O’Neill, The Case for Community Wealth Building, (Polity, 2019). 5 Joseph E. Stiglitz, Rewriting the Rules of the American Economy: An Agenda for Growth and Shared Prosperity, (W. W. Norton & Company, 2015); see also Joseph E. Stiglitz, 2018, ‘Weak economic recovery was down to flawed policies, not secular stagnation’, The Guardian, 29 August 2018. 6 Joseph E. Stiglitz 2019, People, Power and Profits: Progressive Capitalism for an Age of Discontent (Allen Lane, 2019), 198. 7 For concrete proposals for predistributive policies, see for example, Roberto Mangabeira Unger, Isaac Stanley, Madeleine Gabriel, and Geoff Mulgan, Imagination Unleashed: Democratising the Knowledge Economy, (NESTA, 2019); Liam Kennedy, ‘The institution’s not for turning? Inequality, taxes and anti-capitalism’, Renewal: a Journal of Social Democracy, 27.3 (2019), 51–59; Liam Kennedy, ‘Inequality: from redistri- bution to predistribution and beyond?’, Social Europe, 2 May 2019, avail- able at ; Paul Gregg, ‘The Potential and Limits of Predistribution in the UK: Tackling Inequality and Poverty’ in The Predistribution Agenda: Tackling Inequality and Supporting Sustainable Growth, (Policy Network, 2015), edited by Claudia Chwalisz and Patrick Diamond, 79–90; Anne Wren, ‘The Political Economy of the Service Transition: New Political Coalitions for Predistributive Strategies’, in Chwalisz and Diamond, op. cit., 222–234. For a somewhat dissenting voice, see Lane Kenworthy, ‘What’s Wrong with Predistribution’, Juncture, 20.2 (2013), 111–17. 8 Thomas Piketty, ‘Capital, Predistribution and Redistribution’ in Crooked Timber Seminar on Thomas Piketty’s Capital in the Twenty-First 65 Power, Predistribution, and Social Justice Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.socialeurope.eu/inequality-socialisation/ https://www.socialeurope.eu/inequality-socialisation/ https://www.cambridge.org/core questioning the conceptual distinction between the two categories: an issue that will be explored in detail in what follows here. This increasing academic concern with predistribution runs paral- lel with developments in the world of practical politics. Traditional models of social democracy have come under pressure as support for welfare state institutions have weakened, leaving a scepticism about familiar forms of redistribution, together with a lack of clarity about what the most promising alternatives to such policies might be. Moreover, with runaway levels of inequality within the rich industrialised countries, it seems increasingly implausible that familiar forms of redistributive, tax-and-spend centre-left politics can any longer be adequate to the task of creating a more just and equitable economic settlement. The lack of clear ideas to animate a new centre-left vision of the role of the state has been associated, in many countries, with a fall in support for mainstream social demo- cratic parties, as we see with the travails of parties such as the French Parti Socialiste, or the German SPD.9 While the US Democratic Party has its own distinct history, placing it at some distance from the mainstream currents of global social democracy, ideas of predistribution have also gained some pur- chase within that party, especially on its more radical wing. A January 2019 New York Times article by Steven K. Vogel, a political scientist based at UC Berkeley, explains the economic policies at the centre of Senator Elizabeth Warren’s policy platform for her 2020 Presidential bid as itself being organised around an idea of predistribution. As the NY Times headline puts it, ‘Elizabeth Warren Wants to Stop Inequality Before It Starts: Redistribution is important, but comes too late’.10 The idea of predistribution has therefore been seen as offering a way forward for progressive and social democratic parties of the left Century, edited by Henry Farrell, 90–107. Available at . See also Martin O’Neill, ‘Philosophy and Public Policy after Piketty’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 25.3 (2017), 343–375. 9 See Thomas Piketty, Capital et Idéologie (Éditions du Seuil, 2019); Stephanie Mudge, Leftism Reinvented: Western Parties from Socialism to Neoliberalism (Harvard University Press, 2018); Wolfgang Streeck, Buying Time: the Delayed Crisis of Democratic Capitalism (Verso Books, 2014), Ashley Lavelle, The Death of Social Democracy: Political Consequences in the 21st Century (Ashgate, 2008). 10 Steven K. Vogel, ‘Elizabeth Warren Wants to Stop Inequality Before It Starts’, The New York Times, 3 January 2019. 66 Martin O’Neill Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. http://crookedtimber.org/wp-content/uploads/2016/01/piketty-final.pdf http://crookedtimber.org/wp-content/uploads/2016/01/piketty-final.pdf http://crookedtimber.org/wp-content/uploads/2016/01/piketty-final.pdf https://www.cambridge.org/core and centre-left, finding a way of moving beyond political strategies that seem to have run out of steam. Patrick Diamond and Claudia Chwalisz of the think tank Policy Network, which brings together social democratic parties across the globe, go so far as to describe pre- distribution as offering ‘a new governing prospectus for the centre- left’.11 The idea has, indeed, been taken up by politicians from a range of European social democratic parties, as well as by politicians from the Australian and New Zealand Labor Parties.12 Perhaps most famously, or notoriously, the idea of predistribution was invoked by former UK Labour leader Ed Miliband as a central organising theme of the Labour Party’s economic policy during his leadership, with a focus on reforms to corporate governance (with worker representation on boards) and government procurement practices (to drive up wages and incentivise private sector investment in skills development).13 Although the idea became somewhat muted in the run-up to the 2015 general election in the UK, the idea of emphasising underlying institutional changes to the economy, rather than relying on fiscal re- distribution, has retained its currency as pointing a path forward in the achievement of more just societies in the decades after the end of the social democratic era.14 Having given a sense of the relevant background, both intellectual and political, the aim of this article is to apply some analytical rigour to the idea of predistribution, and to offer a diagnosis of whether it really does describe a distinct and coherent set of policies, to be dis- tinguished from the more familiar forms of redistribution that have traditionally been championed by the centre-left. Only by getting a 11 Claudia Chwalisz and Patrick Diamond, ‘Predistribution: A New Governing Prospectus for the Centre-Left,’ in The Predistribution Agenda: Tackling Inequality and Supporting Sustainable Growth, edited by Claudia Chwalisz and Patrick Diamond, (I. B. Tauris, 2015). 12 See for example Jim Chalmers, ‘Labor and the Tools of Success’, in Not Dead Yet: What Future for Labor? by Mark Latham (Black Inc, 2013); and Penny Wong, ‘Australians Shouldn’t Have to Choose between Growth and Fairness’, The Guardian, 19 May 2014. 13 See Martin O’Neill and Thad Williamson, ‘Philosophical Foundations for ‘Good Capitalism’’, Renewal: a Journal of Social Democracy, 20.1, 2012, 20–32. 14 Ed Miliband, ‘The Inequality Problem’, London Review of Books, 38 (3), 2016, 19–20. See also Eunice Goes, The Labour Party Under Ed Miliband: Trying but Failing to Renew Social Democracy (Manchester University Press, 2016), and Joe Guinan and Martin O’Neill, ‘The Institutional Turn: Labour’s New Political Economy’, Renewal, 26 (2), 2018, 5–16, esp. at 7. 67 Power, Predistribution, and Social Justice Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core clear sense of what may or may not be distinctive in the idea of pre- distribution, and, relatedly, whether there is a fundamental distinc- tion between predistributive and redistributive forms of public policy, can we assess whether, as some of those mentioned above might believe, the idea of ‘predistribution’ could serve as an import- ant organising idea for thinking about the future of egalitarian public policy. I shall argue that there are considerable conceptual problems with most common ways in which the contours of the idea of predistribu- tion have been articulated, not least because it is difficult to find an unproblematic way in which to distinguish between predistributive and redistributive forms of public policy. In establishing this claim, my approach will be somewhat dialectical, starting not from an ab- stract conceptual foundation, but encountering the idea of predistri- bution in media res, working through some of the initially plausible but ultimately unsuccessful ways that the idea has been presented. Nevertheless, I shall argue that it is possible to rescue the idea of pre- distribution from the conceptual quagmire into which it might be in danger of falling, if we look to reconstruct it – again in a somewhat dialectical fashion – by first challenging and then redrawing its boundaries. This reconstruction of the idea of predistribution allows us to lay out the idea of predistribution as an important strand in thinking about the potential of a more egalitarian political economy. While my discussion will touch upon the pre-history of predistribution, I begin with the recent history of the idea. 2. The Recent Conceptual History of Predistribution: Jacob Hacker on the ‘Institutional Foundations of Middle-Class Democracy’ Although one can find one or two earlier uses of the term predistribu- tion15, conceived as an alternative approach to standard forms of redistribution, the recent use of the term dates back to a 2011 paper delivered at the Progressive Governance Conference in Oslo by the political scientist Jacob Hacker, on ‘The Institutional Foundations of Middle-Class Democracy’; Hacker has, since then, rightly come to be seen as the central and pre-eminent academic advocate of the 15 James Robertson, ‘The Future of Money: If We Want a Better Game of Life, We’ll Have to Change the Scoring System’, Soundings, 31 (2005), 118–32 68 Martin O’Neill Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core idea of predistribution.16 In this article, Hacker is looking to draw on the lessons of his book co-authored with Paul Pierson, Winner-Take- All Politics17, in terms of its implications for how progressive politi- cians should look to correct for the increasingly inegalitarian charac- ter of the economic settlement in the advanced industrial countries.18 Hacker introduces the idea of predistribution as one of three strands in his diagnosis of what had gone wrong in the past with regard to growing inequality, and therefore as an aspect of the eco- nomic situation ‘crucial for grasping – and overcoming – the chal- lenges that progressives face today’.19 Here is his characterisation of the idea: ‘The first feature is the role of pre-distribution. When we think of government’s effects on inequality, we think of redistribution – government taxes and transfers that take from some and give to others. Yet many of the most important changes have been in what might be called “pre-distribution” – the way in which the market distributes its rewards in the first place. Policies governing financial markets, the rights of unions and the pay of top execu- tives have all shifted in favour of those at the top … The moral of this story is that progressive reformers need to focus on market reforms that encourage a more equal distribution of eco- nomic power and rewards even before government collects taxes or pays out benefits. This is not just because pre-distribution is where the action is. It is also because excessive reliance on 16 Jacob S. Hacker, ‘The Institutional Foundations of Middle-Class Democracy,’ in Priorities for a New Political Economy: Memos to the Left, (Policy Network, 2011), 33–38. Hacker here is using the term ‘middle- class’ in its sense in American English, rather than its sense in British English. 17 Jacob S. Hacker and Paul Pierson, Winner-Take-All Politics: How Washington Made the Rich Richer – And Turned Its Back on the Middle Class, (Simon & Schuster, 2010). 18 A caveat about my argumentative strategy: In this section and the two sections that follow, I shall put quite a degree of pressure on Hacker’s at- tempts to give more definite shape to the intuitive distinction between pre- distribution and redistribution. But this is not intended as criticism of Hacker per se: he has done a great deal to develop an important public policy agenda in this area, and his ways of articulating the conceptual dis- tinction between these kinds of policies are valuable in pointing us towards intuitively appealing, if ultimately unstable, ways of thinking about these issues. 19 Op. cit. note 13, 35. 69 Power, Predistribution, and Social Justice Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core redistribution fosters backlash, making taxes more salient and feeding into the conservative critique that government simply meddles with “natural” market rewards.’20 (my italics) Hacker is giving us two reasons for switching our concern from redis- tribution to predistribution: (a) predistribution is simply of greater fundamental importance than redistribution, because it reflects more deep-seated features of how the economy functions – i.e. it is ‘where the action is’; and (b) notwithstanding the more fundamental nature of predistribution over redistribution, it is anyway the case that there are instrumental reasons to turn away from traditional redis- tributive policies, for such policies foster ‘backlash’ and can be counter-productive in terms of feeding the kinds of conservative and anti-egalitarian political sentiments that undermine support for progressive or egalitarian politics. Let us call these the fundamental case for predistribution and the instrumental case. I take it that Hacker takes both considerations – fundamental and instrumental – to operate in tandem, presumably overdetermining his advice for centre-left politicians and political parties. Before assessing the substance of either the fundamental or the in- strumental case for predistribution, though, I want first to pause to ask whether this characterisation of predistribution can be seen as passing muster in terms of determinateness and coherence. Hacker’s characterisation of predistribution is that it is constituted by ‘market reforms that encourage a more equal distribution of eco- nomic power even before government collects taxes or pays out benefits’. (my italics) But it is not clear how we should understand that char- acterisation, once we begin to put some pressure on it. There are, in fact, two ways in which this characterisation might seem to be both confused and confusing, and hence two clear objections that one can make to it. I’ll call these the temporal objection and the Murphy- Nagel objection, and will take them in turn. Firstly, the temporal objection. If read in its literal sense, the talk of before and after with regard to the tax system simply does not stand up. It is not that economic activity somehow takes place within a dis- crete time period, with the government standing outside the eco- nomic domain while these processes take place, only stepping in at the end of each period, so to speak, in order to collect taxes and pay out benefits, so that a new discrete period of economic activity can then take place. Rather, economic activity is an endlessly ongoing process, with the government’s activities as both collector of taxes 20 Op. cit. note 13, 35. 70 Martin O’Neill Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core and payer of benefits a similarly continuous, if periodically modulat- ing, constitutive part of that process. The temporal objection then, is that talk of ‘before’ and ‘after’ with regard to government’s role in economic life, while it has a certain kind of brisk initial plausibility, is on further investigation merely mystifying.21 A second objection takes a step back, allowing that this temporal language of ‘before’ and ‘after’ should not be read literally. One can grant that the distinction between economic activity and government tax-and-spend should not be understood in temporal terms, because the two are always temporally intertwined, while nevertheless thinking that there is an important distinction to be made between economic ac- tivity considered on its own terms, conceptually if not temporally prior to government intervention, and the same activity taking place within the context of a regime of government tax-and-spend activity. But even if the terrain here shifts from the temporal to the conceptual, a different variant of the same kind of problem remains. In their book The Myth of Ownership: Taxes and Justice, Liam Murphy and Thomas Nagel diagnose the conceptual errors embed- ded in the view they call ‘everyday libertarianism’.22 This is, in effect, the view that there is a domain of economic activity, free of government intervention, that has conceptual (if not temporal) prior- ity over really existing economic activity that takes place in the pres- ence of government tax-and-spending. This ‘everyday libertarian’ fallacy explains what goes wrong when an individual thinks of their pre-tax income as in some sense robustly all ‘theirs’, with government intervention through the tax system then conceptualised as the expro- priation of something that would otherwise belong to them. As 21 For a related discussion of the conceptual problems of temporal meta- phors for thinking about the way that the state structures economic activity, see Martin O’Neill, ‘Free (and Fair) Markets without Capitalism: Political Values, Principles of Justice, and Property-Owning Democracy,’ in Martin O’Neill and Thad Williamson, eds., Property-Owning Democracy: Rawls and Beyond, (Wiley-Blackwell, 2012), 75–100, esp. 87–91. 22 Liam Murphy and Thomas Nagel, The Myth of Ownership: Taxes and Justice, (Oxford University Press, 2002). For critical discussion of Murphy and Nagel’s idea of ‘everyday libertarianism’, see Marc Fleurbaey, ‘Welfarism, Libertarianism, and Fairness in the Economic Approach to Taxation’, in Martin O’Neill and Shepley Orr, eds., Taxation: Philosophical Perspectives, (Oxford University Press, 2018), 37–59; Geoffrey Brennan, ‘Striving for the Middle Ground: Taxation, Justice, and the State of Private Rights’, in O’Neill and Orr, op. cit., 60–80; and Laura Biron, ‘Taxing or Taking? Property Rhetoric and the Justice of Taxation’, in O’Neill and Orr, op. cit., 81–97. 71 Power, Predistribution, and Social Justice Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core Murphy and Nagel point out, what counts as somebody’s property is itself defined by the full system of property rights, of which the tax system is a part. The tax system is not some alien extrusion into the property system, but a constitutive part of it. Moreover, given that an individual’s market earnings will typically depend on a back- ground of legal, social and physical infrastructure – from contract-en- forcement to public roads – which itself depends on the tax system, it is not as if there exists some kind of normatively privileged possible world in which we somehow can have the benefits of the tax system without being taxed, and against which we should set the normative benchmark of our property entitlements. Hence, what we might call the Murphy-Nagel objection to Hacker’s initial characterisation of predistribution is that there is something confused in talk of economic distributions ‘before government collects taxes or pays out benefits’ even when that before is understood as in- dicating a kind of conceptual rather than temporal priority. The mys- tification may be of a slightly different kind, but it persists in moving from the temporal reading of the phrase to the conceptual reading. Moreover, there would be an odd tension in Hacker’s position if it were to need to make use of this kind of conceptual prioritisation of pre- tax-and-spend economic activity. For bear in mind that, in Hacker’s instrumental case for the shift in focus from redistribution to predistribution, his argument is that the backlash fostered by redis- tributive policies feeds into ‘the conservative critique that government meddles with “natural” market rewards’. In other words, the political psychology of redistribution, in which people resent the government’s apparent appropriation of ‘their’ pre-tax income, is one that involves, and indeed reinforces, the conceptually muddled ‘everyday libertarian’ view to which Murphy and Nagel take exception. Given that Hacker’s instrumental objection to redistributive politics is that it feeds this muddled way of thinking about the relationship between government activity and economic rewards, it would therefore be odd if Hacker’s canonical characterisation of predistribution – conceived as an alterna- tive strategy to familiar forms of redistribution – itself embedded its own version of this same kind of conceptual mistake. 3. A Better Account of Predistribution? Tax-and-Spend vs Market-Shaping Hacker gives a broader and less mystifying characterisation of predis- tribution in a 2013 interview on ‘The Politics of Predistribution’: 72 Martin O’Neill Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core ‘[Predistribution] is a very basic idea. It is that government has an enormous range of ways in which it can shape the distribution of income and opportunity in a society that are distinct from simply taxing and providing benefits. […] (my italics) Markets are deeply shaped by government. And over the last gen- eration markets have been shaped in ways that have benefited those at the top far more than those in the middle and bottom. If we are going to have an effective, progressive agenda for the future, we are going to have to think about how to use these ways in which government shapes markets to pursue progressive goals. By progressive goals I mean, first and foremost, broad growth in the economy that translates into social and economic gains for citizens across the income distribution.’23 (my italics) This is a happier, less problematic characterisation of the core of the idea of predistribution, given not in terms of what can be done before or after government tax-and-spend, but instead putting things more simply in terms of what government can do (a) ‘to shape the dis- tribution of income and opportunity’ (b) ‘that are distinct from simply taxing and providing benefits’. The characterisation of predistributive policies simply as being distinct from, rather than either temporally or conceptually prior, dismisses the two kinds of worries discussed previ- ously. We seem therefore to have here at least a provisionally satisfac- tory characterisation of the idea of predistribution. Nevertheless, it is worth noting a problem with talk of the ‘ways in which it can shape the distribution of income and opportunity in a society that are distinct from simply taxing and providing benefits’ when considered at face value, which is that there is nothing in such a charac- terisation that capturesthe idea of predistribution as a substantively pro- gressive or egalitarian kind of policy. Consider the case of what one might call ‘inegalitarian predistribution’, using a semi-imaginary country that I’ll call Ukania, as a way of illustrating the distinction between formal and substantive understandings of predistribution: The Case of Ukania Ukania has strong labour unions and a relatively compressed income distribution. Organised labour is politically strong when negotiating 23 Jacob S. Hacker, Ben Jackson and Martin O’Neill, ‘Interview: the Politics of Predistribution’, Renewal, 21 (2/3), 54–64, at 54. 73 Power, Predistribution, and Social Justice Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core with employers, keeping the capital share of national income rela- tively low. After a general election, a radically anti-egalitarian, ‘pro- business’ government enacts a range of economic policies, including reducing both current and investment spending in public services, and reducing the top rate of income tax (with this latter policy being the one to receive most attention from Ukania’s political philo- sophers24). But at least as important as these changes to the tax-and- spend regime, the government also undertakes a number of measures that we might describe as instances of (formal) predistribution, which are distinct from changes to taxation or benefits. For example, the gov- ernment makes it more difficult for workers to take industrial action, thereby weakening the bargaining power of labour unions, and makes it easier for employers to sack workers, thereby making individual workers more fearful of their economic security and less liable to indulge in industrial militancy. The effect of these (formally) predis- tributive policies is to reshape the power dynamics of the labour market, thereby attenuating the income distribution as managers and entrepreneurs begin to find their economic rewards accelerating away from those of ordinary workers, while also leading to a shift in the balance between labour and capital in their shares of the distribu- tion of national income. The case of Ukania shows that there is nothing in the formal idea of non-tax-and-spend government interventions in market regulation that necessarily aligns with progressive or egalitarian goals. Plenty that a government might do that is not tax-and-spend, from weaken- ing vacation entitlements to lowering minimum wage levels, could lessen the income or opportunities of those people within the economy who were already relatively disadvantaged. Therefore, as we work our way towards a more precise characterisation of the idea of predistribution, it will be worth making a stipulation that what we have in mind is not merely predistribution in the formal sense – under which the government of Reagan and Thatcher in the US and UK could count as striking examples of effective predistributive public policy – but a more substantive idea of predistribution that in- volves the pursuit of broadly progressive or egalitarian goals. Obviously there could be different ways of spelling out the precise nature of those goals, and this is something to which we shall return later in this discussion. Hacker offers one example in talking about ‘economic and social gains for citizens across the income 24 In the vein of the discussion in G. A. Cohen’s work on inequality, in- centives and marginal tax rates. See op. cit. note 2. 74 Martin O’Neill Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core distribution’, which one might see as a fairly minimalist characterisa- tion of a progressive aim, leaving open the space for more ambitious rival views. But the main stipulation is that, in talking about predis- tribution from here onwards, it will be the substantive idea of a broadly progressive or egalitarian form of predistribution that will be in view, rather than the kind of merely formal idea of predistribu- tion under which the regressive policies of our Ukanian example would qualify as a case of predistribution par excellence. This stipula- tion is driven by the nature of the investigation at hand: the fact that we are starting from a really-existing debate among advocates of a more progressive or egalitarian economic settlement, and that it is from that debate that the idea of predistribution has emerged. To return to our provisional characterisation, making use of Hacker’s revised definition and pre-empting the problem of merely formal forms of predistribution, we can define predistributive policies as those that pursue progressive or egalitarian ends (however precisely those are to be characterised) by means of government action distinct from taxing and providing benefits. This position certainly on the face of it seems clear and determinate. But I want to suggest that things get much more complicated as soon as we try to investigate the question of whether there is really an important distinction in kind between government action that involves taxation and spending, and government action that involves distinct mechanisms that shape markets and the location of power within those markets. The potential problem for our provisional position here is that there is a danger that the category of predistributive policies – and hence the idea of predis- tribution itself – may end up relying on a distinction without a real underlying difference. It is to this question that we shall now turn. 4. The Plot Thickens: the Predistributive Function of Public Services For a paradigm case of predistribution, let’s return to our semi-im- aginary Ukania, and imagine the accession to power in that country of a new government which is resolutely sympathetic to labour unions and enacts a number of measures to increase union density, to make industrial action easier, and to embed the role of unions in sectoral pay bargaining, on something of the model of codetermin- ation or Mitbestimmung as we see in models of Rhenish capitalism.25 25 Peter A. Hall and David Soskice, eds., Varieties of Capitalism: The Institutional Foundations of Comparative Advantage, (Oxford University 75 Power, Predistribution, and Social Justice Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core Let us imagine, as is likely, that these reforms greatly increase the bar- gaining power of labour relative to capital. In John Kenneth Galbraith’s terms, such reforms would grant ordinary workers a form of ‘countervailing power’ with regard to their employ- ers.26 The predictable consequences of such reforms, other things being equal, would be that labour would be able to claim more of the division of the social surplus, the gap in wages between ordinary workers and their bosses would reduce, and inequality would go down. Thus we have here a clear paradigm case of predistributive public policy (in the full substantive sense). Nevertheless, if we’re interested in what governments do to shape markets, and to change the balance of bargaining power between dif- ferent groups or classes within the economy, then that does not give us a special category of action that is distinct from taxation and public spending, but seems to include it, in particular when we think about redistribution through the provision of public services. Consider a different example, where the provision of public services also changes the relevant power dynamics between workers and employ- ers. Let’s call this example the Case of USania. The Case of USania Imagine a society in which healthcare benefits are provided in a hap- hazard way by an inefficient system of private insurance, with many people’s access to even a minimally decent level of healthcare provi- sion being tied to their employment status. Imagine that in such a society, against all previous expectations, a democratic socialist candi- date is elected to the presidency, and that one of his or her first policy priorities is to create a national health system that ensures that all workers have access to an excellent level of universally available healthcare, provided free at the point of use through direct public provision, funded by general taxation. What would be the implica- tions enacting this kind of policy? Well, obviously something would have to happen to the tax system in order to fund this new system, and the new system would bring benefits to many individuals who were comparatively disadvantaged by the previous system. Press, 2001); Thomas Piketty, Capital in the Twenty-First Century, (Harvard University Press, 2014), 140–46. 26 John Kenneth Galbraith, American Capitalism: The Concept of Countervailing Power, (Houghton Mifflin, 1952). 76 Martin O’Neill Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core No doubt there would be some general efficiency gains in moving from a splintered private market to a coherent public system of healthcare provision, and so there would be a certain amount of ‘lev- elling up’, and the removal of the deadweight loss associated with the rent-seeking private bureaucracies associated with the previous system. What there would also be, in terms of direct effects, would be a de facto economic transfer from those who were especially advan- taged by the old system (e.g. by the unreasonable suppression of top rates of taxation) towards those relatively disadvantaged individuals who would be most advantaged by the new system. But something else would happen as well, which would directly parallel what would happen when Ukania moved towards a more Rhenish or Nordic model of employment relationships. The bargain- ing power of labour would go up. When workers’ access to healthcare depended directly on their employment status, and where employers had a role as gatekeepers in terms of access to more adequate and at- tractive health insurance plans, workers obviously had a direct incen- tive against ‘rocking the boat’ in their workplace, given that the effective costs of even a short period of unemployment could be so high. By contrast, after the enactment of our imagined National Health Service – or Medicare for All – in USania, the costs of exiting from a bad employment relationship would be much lower for workers, and hence their bargaining power against their employers would go up, in much the same kind of way as if a change had been made more directly to the regulation of that employment relationship. The tax-funded provision of public services is not of interest to progressives or egalitarians only because it is directly a way of benefit- ting everyone at a cost that falls disproportionately on those who have more, but also because of second-round effects that the provision of public services can have in terms of the structure and distribution of power in economic relationships within that society. The public provision of services such as healthcare, education, and childcare, or even provision of goods such as public transportation and public parks,27 creates the background conditions against which different groups and different sectional interests fight their corner and negoti- ate their economic relationships. Public provision is not just a way of 27 Joshua Cohen, ‘On Central Park’, Gilded Birds, 2 January 2013, avail- able at ; Bonnie Honig, Public Things: Democracy in Disrepair (Fordham University Press, 2017). See also the Labour Party Report, Universal Basic Services: The Right to a Good Life, (Labour Party, 2019), available at . 77 Power, Predistribution, and Social Justice Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://gildedbirds.com/2013/01/02/joshua-cohen/ https://gildedbirds.com/2013/01/02/joshua-cohen/ http://www.labour.org.uk/universalbasicservices/ http://www.labour.org.uk/universalbasicservices/ http://www.labour.org.uk/universalbasicservices/ https://www.cambridge.org/core undertaking a transfer against the backdrop of a market with a par- ticular kind of shape and structure, it is also at the same time a means of shaping markets, and changing the relative bargaining power of different groups of market actors. Therefore, if predistribu- tion is centrally about the role of government in what we might call ‘market-shaping’, then there is not a relevant contrast to be drawn with a different kind of activity (imagined presumably as purely redis- tributive) that government undertakes when it goes in for the provi- sion of public services funded by taxation. Public service provision is in general both about transferring benefits, per se, but also about shaping the background within which market transactions take place, and therefore it is misleading rather than illuminating to draw a sharp contrast, at the levels of types of policy, between policies that have a redistributive role and those that have a ‘market-shaping’ role. A pessimistic diagnosis at this point is that the idea of predistribu- tion as presented in Hacker’s revised and more promising formula- tion ends up trading on a merely shallow distinction between different kinds of government action. If it turns out that precisely what is interesting about the predistributive effects of changes in labour regulation can also be seen at work in the classically ‘redis- tributive’ provision of public services, then we apparently do not have a way of dividing government policies that affect economic outcomes neatly into the two categories of ‘redistribution’ and ‘predistribution’. Advocates of predistribution as the proper zone of focus for progressive or egalitarian politics, in distinction to the previous focus on redistribution, might therefore be seen as relying upon a superficial conceptual distinction that does not illuminate a deeper contrast in how policies function. 5. Power, Public Services, and a Pluralist Account of Predistribution Stepping back from the characterisation of predistribution that has been found wanting, we should note that Jacob Hacker is, of course, fully aware of the market-shaping and power-rebalancing effects of public service provision, and does not fall into the trap of seeing such policies in purely redistributive terms, without being aware of their more ‘predistributive’ function. In another presentation of the core idea of predistribution, presented in a BBC Radio 4 Analysis pro- gramme on the subject, Hacker pursues the thought (which seems to have some intellectual kinship with the thinking of both Michael 78 Martin O’Neill Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core Walzer and T. H. Marshall28) that the provision of certain important public services will be valuable precisely for the reason that such pro- vision will reduce the salience and significance of market inequalities. Here, then, is this third account of the idea of predistribution: ‘You have to ask what are the central ways in which government can stand on the side of ordinary workers that do not involve taxing and providing benefits, and I would say that there are three. One, it means getting the macro economy right. When we’re closer to full employment as an economy … we tend to get stronger wage growth across the board. It also means making sure that even if inequality’s growing in the market, it matters less in terms of some vital public services - things like health- care, childcare. And, finally, it means – and this is the hardest part – it means trying to make sure that in an era in which orga- nised labour is weaker that labour still has a voice and a place. And whether that’s supporting living wage campaigns, whether that means providing new opportunities for workers to have a voice outside of unions, whether it means if we privatise public services or contract out and allow all these low wage jobs to pro- liferate in and around the public sector, we’re making our job much, much harder’.29 (my italics) Here we have a more complicated or pluralist conception of what is meant by predistribution. I take it that the idea of ‘getting the macro- economy right’ and avoiding the kind of contractionary austerity as- sociated with UK economic policy in the years following the 2008 financial crisis, is uncontroversial common ground between the advo- cates of different varieties of progressive political economy, whether self-avowedly ‘redistributive’ or ‘predistributive’ in character. The more interesting elements are the second and third. The idea of making sure ‘that labour still has a voice and a place’ looks like a ca- nonical case of predistributive market-shaping, in ensuring, as in our Ukanian example above, that the organised power of labour can be a source of Galbraithian countervailing power within the economy. Let’s call this ‘labour predistribution’, which I now take to be an un- problematic dimension of the idea of predistribution. 28 Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice, (Basic Books, 1984); T. H. Marshall, Citizenship and Social Class, (Cambridge University Press, 1950). 29 BBC Analysis, ‘Predistribution’, 17 June 2013. Transcript available at: 79 Power, Predistribution, and Social Justice Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. http://downloads.bbc.co.uk/radio4/transcripts/20130620-analysis-predistribution.pdf http://downloads.bbc.co.uk/radio4/transcripts/20130620-analysis-predistribution.pdf http://downloads.bbc.co.uk/radio4/transcripts/20130620-analysis-predistribution.pdf https://www.cambridge.org/core The most interesting case, though, is the middle one, which, rather than being a classic case of ‘labour predistribution’, sees the provision of public services as a central plank of predistributive public policy. What is worth noting about such policies is that the predistributive dimension of public service provision has a dual aspect. On the one hand, as in cases like our imagined USanian health service, public service provision changes the distribution of power within market in- teractions between employers and employees. But on the other hand, as Hacker points out, such public service provision, by straightfor- wardly making individuals less reliant on their market income to provide for the vital necessities of life, also simply reduces the salience and significance of market inequalities. Obviously these two effects are related to one another in how they function, but it is worth keeping them analytically distinct. The very same policies can be at- tractive to progressives and egalitarians both because they reallocate market power, changing the terms on which market transactions take place so as to make them more egalitarian in their outcomes, and also because they reduce the importance of market incomes for individuals who can also rely on non-market social entitlements. The first aspect is shared with central cases of ‘labour predistribu- tion’, whereas the second element – lessening individuals’ reliance on the labour market considered as valuable not merely because this will increase individuals’ bargaining power within the labour market – is a distinctive variety of predistribution which could not be enacted by labour predistribution alone. Where does this leave us? On the one hand, it is important to have a clear sense of the significance this dual aspect of predistribution, and of the non-derivative value of increasing workers’ power, and lessening their vulnerability, within the labour market. This shows why it would not be plausible to circumscribe the ambit of predistributive policies so as to exclude predistributive tax-and-benefit policies. On the other hand, this seems to lead us back into our earlier conceptual difficulties, unable to identify a coherent specific category of predistri- butive policies, held distinct from their redistributive alternatives. 6. The Predistributive Role of Taxation and Cash Transfers Before adjudicating on this conceptual issue, I want first to consider a potentially enlightening final proposal, which takes seriously the im- plications of the predistributive role of public services. The proposal is that where we should draw the distinction between predistribution and redistribution is that, whereas the former includes both market- 80 Martin O’Neill Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core shaping regulations and the provision of public services (which both increase workers’ bargaining power in their labour market transac- tions and reduce workers’ reliance on those transactions), it excludes the kinds of pure case of fiscal tax-and-transfer that are an essential element of regimes of redistribution. The case for progressives fa- vouring predistribution over redistribution could then be recast as a case in favour of pursuing a combined strategy of market regulation and the provision of in-kind benefits, as opposed to pursing simple cash transfers. To assess this proposal, I want to take one clear and unambiguous example of a policy of redistributive cash transfer, and one clear example of a policy of altering top-rate income taxation. Even for such pure cases of tax-and-transfer, I will argue that on further investigation both have a dimension that is best understood as ‘predistributive’, such that neither policy can be fully understood in purely redistributive terms. I’ll take the cases in turn. (a) The Predistributive Case for Universal Basic Income There could be no policy that fits more centrally under the descrip- tion of redistribution than a tax-funded cash transfer, of the kind that would be paid unconditionally under proposals for an uncondi- tional universal basic income (UBI). Such policies can be justified in different ways, by means of appeal to different foundational norma- tive principles.30 But it is striking that some plausible justifications for such a paradigmatically redistributive policy depend precisely on the twin ‘predistributive’ effects that such redistributive policies can have. The individual in receipt of a (relatively high) uncondi- tional basic income is, by virtue of receiving that income, likely (a) to have more bargaining power in the labour market than she would otherwise have, and (b) to be less reliant on how she fares in the labour market, and hence less vulnerable to market outcomes. Karl Widerquist, a leading defender of UBI policies, in his book Independence, Propertylessness and Basic Income, justifies UBI on broadly republican grounds, in terms of its giving individuals ‘freedom as the power to say ‘‘no’’’.31 Whilst this does not preclude UBI having other sources of possible egalitarian justification, 30 See Philippe Van Parijs and Yannick Vanderborght, Basic Income: A Radical Proposal for a Free Society and a Sane Economy (Harvard University Press, 2017), Ch. 5. 31 Karl Widerquist, Independence, Propertylessness and Basic Income: A Theory of Freedom as the Power to Say No, (Palgrave, 2013). 81 Power, Predistribution, and Social Justice Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core perhaps more closely aligned with its directly redistributive character, this form of republican defence of UBI turns on its ‘second-round’ pre- distributive dimension. The recipient of a (relatively high) UBI will find herself more robustly secure outside of how she fares in the labour market, which may be non-derivatively valuable to her as well as being derivatively valuable in terms of this granting her greater power as an actor within the labour market. Where UBI is universal, and all workers are similarly situated, the bargaining power of labour over capital will increase, just in the same way as in canonical cases of ‘labour predistribution’. And so here even the purest case of a redis- tributive policy can find justification on predistributive grounds. (b) Predistribution and Top-Rate Income Tax: the Piketty-Saez- Stantcheva Effect It is also significant that the justification of some forms of taxation can turn not on the role of those taxes in raising revenue for the fiscal authorities, but simply on their paradigmatically ‘predistribu- tive’ effects in terms of the market bargaining-power of the best paid. This may seem surprising at first sight, given that so much of public and even academic discussion of top marginal tax rates pro- ceeds with the unarticulated assumption that the primary function of such taxes is in their ‘first-round’ effects in revenue raising, hence embroiling us immediately in the over-simplified and rather short-sighted discussion of the shape of the relevant Laffer curves, and our current position with respect to them. But the indirect effects of tax are often just as important, including those that work through effects on the allocation of bargaining power. This will be clearer if we consider what we can call the Piketty- Saez-Stantcheva effect of changes in top marginal rates of income taxation. In their modelling of top rates, Piketty, Saez and Stantcheva find that the determination of top rates of pay is not best understood in terms of standard marginal productivity theory. This is not only because of the formidable epistemic barriers to deter- mining what the marginal contribution of corporate managers or other very highly paid workers actually is, at least outside of specific domains such as the entertainment industry or professional sport,32 but also because more can be explained in terms of a ‘bargaining 32 As Thomas Piketty rather charmingly puts it in Capital in the Twenty-First Century, ‘the theory of marginal productivity runs into serious conceptual and economic difficulties (in addition to suffering from 82 Martin O’Neill Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core model’ of top pay.33 In short, senior managers get what they can bargain their way to getting, given the behaviour of others and the prevailing social norms. When top marginal rates of income taxation are very high, with a comparatively large gap between gross and net pay at the top end of the distribution, highly paid workers will be less likely to focus on the extrinsic financial rewards of their positions, and focus more on the intrinsic rewards of prestige and authority in large organisations; conversely, when top marginal rates of taxation are lowered, and the gap between gross and net pay at the top end of the distribution falls, we see a phenomenon where competitive bar- gaining focuses much more on pay rates per se, thereby driving up the costs to companies of their senior managers.34 Hence, we get the Piketty-Saez-Stantcheva effect, whereby de- creases in top marginal rates of taxation drive up not just net rates of top pay, but much more significantly such tax changes greatly drive up gross (pre-tax) levels of top pay as well. This is due to the ways in which these tax changes transform the bargaining situations in which top pay is determined, both in terms of the incentives held by the highly paid themselves, and in terms of background effects on social norms. What we have here, then, is another case of a putatively pure ‘redistributive’ policy mechanism having significant effects through what we might think of as typically ‘predistributive’ me- chanisms. This is, so to speak, the obverse of what happens in the basic income case, where a cash transfer can drive up bargaining power; what we have here is the possibility that the imposition of a higher marginal rate of income tax would be significant not so much for its direct revenue-raising effects, but because it would sig- nificantly reduce the de facto bargaining power of senior and already well-remunerated managers. A classic instance of redistributive eco- nomic policy would turn out, via the best available understanding of the behaviour of the labour market, to be a paradigm case of ‘labour predistribution’, in which the balance of bargaining power in the labour market would be changed, reducing the existing advantages of the small cadre of super-managers and others at the very top end of the distribution of labour income. a certain naïveté) when it comes to explaining how pay is determined at the top of the income hierarchy’. (Piketty op. cit., 509) 33 See Thomas Piketty, Emmauel Saez and Stefanie Stantcheva, ‘Optimal Taxation of Top Labor Incomes: A Tale of Three Elasticities’, American Economic Journal: Economic Policy, 6 (1), 2014, 230–71. 34 Piketty op. cit., 510. 83 Power, Predistribution, and Social Justice Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core Progressives and egalitarians may therefore have very good reasons to champion a significant increase in top rate marginal income taxation, but not only or even mainly for the standard revenue-raising reasons that are typically invoked in the justification of higher taxes on top earn- ings. As Piketty, Saez and Stantcheva put it, ‘the optimal top tax rate increases when there are zero-sum compensation-bargaining effects’.35 This point about the existence of zero-sum bargaining effects is of great importance, but is often overlooked. As Paul Segal points out, there is a very important, if often unacknowledged, way in which we collectively have an interest in keeping down top pay, not out of envy, or even for intrinsically egalitarian reasons, but simply because ‘one way or another, the rest of us have to pay for those incomes: as workers, higher pay at the top means our salaries have to be lower; or as consumers, it raises the prices we face; or as pension- holders, it lowers share prices and profits that fund our retirement’.36 Hence, we return here in a different way to a version of the funda- mental point about taxes made by Murphy and Nagel. Taxes are not some external intrusion into an independently operating economic system, but a constitutive part of the rules of that game; and the struc- ture of the tax system, just as much as the structure of labour law or the array of provision of public services, affects and conditions the relative bargaining powers and positions of different groups and classes of agents within that system. 7. The Collapse of the Distinction between Redistribution and Predistribution? Our conceptual conclusion, then, is that even this much-revised char- acterisation of predistribution fails to pick out a distinct type of policy. Or, to put things in a different way, if we were stipulatively to decide that predistribution should be understood as marking out a class of policies that particularly exclude canonically redistributive tax-and- transfer policies, then we would end up with a category of policies without any underlying coherence at the level of justification, and without any real conceptual or normative interest. There is no 35 Piketty, Saez and Stantcheva, op. cit., 230. 36 Paul Segal, ‘The Problem of Riches’, Renewal, 22 (3/4) (2014), 135–143, at 141. As Segal continues: “Again, since the evidence shows that excessive pay at the top does not increase the size of the pie, their ever-growing slice comes at everyone else’s expense, and trimming it would leave more for the rest of us.” 84 Martin O’Neill Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core interesting or deep distinction at the level of types of policy, as regards the distinction between redistribution and predistribution, given that (a) many policies have both redistributive and predistributive conse- quences, and (b) even the narrow class of pristinely ‘redistributive’ policies, against which the idea of predistribution was characterized by Hacker and others, can themselves have predistributive effects. There is simply no such thing as two distinct categories of policy, one marked redistribution and one marked predistribution. Does this mean that we have simply been on a wild goose chase in thinking through the idea of predistribution, seen as an alternative to traditional forms of redistribution? Thankfully this is not the case. What we have shown is that, insofar as there is an important distinction here, it hasto bewith regard to the aims and effects of policy, rather than in terms of the nature of the policy tools or mechanisms that are used. The content of these policy aims and effects has already been touched upon above, in imagining the new USanian healthcare or Medicare service, and its potential twin roles in both reducing objectionable in- equalities of power within market relationships, and giving individuals a secure standing outside of the market transactions in which they may otherwise be potentially vulnerable to a troubling degree. To get a clearer sense of these predistributive policy aims, I want very briefly to revisit a thinker whom one can see as a highly significant theorist of predistribution avant la lettre: the Nobel Prize winning economist James Meade. In seeing what was at stake Meade’s critique of redistri- bution, we can hope to get a clear fix on what is at stake between advo- cates of predistribution and redistribution, now reconceived as aims or objectives of policy, rather than as distinct kinds of policy. 8. The Pre-History of Predistribution: James Meade on the Twin Aims of Predistribution In his important 1964 book, Efficiency, Equality, and the Ownership of Property, James Meade advanced a compelling account of how wealth should be treated by institutions tasked with creating a more egalitarian economy.37 This work has been influential both on polit- ical philosophers – especially in John Rawls’s ideas of a ‘property- owing democracy’ – and on Meade’s fellow economists, in particular through the work of Anthony Atkinson and Thomas Piketty, the 37 J. E. Meade, Efficiency, Equality and the Ownership of Property, (George Allen & Unwin, 1964), 85 Power, Predistribution, and Social Justice Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core latter of whom describes his own work as ‘following in the footsteps’ of Atkinson and Meade.38 Meade is an interesting figure in the development of thinking about predistribution not least because he was in fact sceptical about the central form of ‘labour predistribution’ that would be involved in bidding-up the bargaining power of labour unions through having pol- itically stronger unions – what he described as enacting a ‘Trade Union State’. His argument was that the costs in overall aggregate economic ef- ficiency of bidding up the price of wages were unjustifiable, and hence an egalitarian economy would have to be sought bysome other means.39 His alternative to ‘labour predistribution’ was to change the character of the overall economic distribution, and therefore also the social relation- ships and distribution of power to which it would give rise, via mechan- isms of what we might call ‘capital predistribution’. He saw the role of the state not in merely ameliorating the poverty of those who did not inherit any of society’s wealth, but in making sure that all citizens within a society would benefit from capital returns. This ‘capital predis- tribution’ would be achieved by a mixture of private means – the creation of ‘a property-owning democracy’ in Meade’s terms – operat- ing simultaneously alongside a ‘socialist state’ that would expand the collective, public ownership of capital through institutions akin to contemporary sovereign wealth funds (or, as Meade put it ‘a national asset’ or ‘Citizens’ Trust’). Meade described the combination of these public and private forms of capital predistribution as together bringing about a form of ‘liberal socialism’.40 38 Piketty op. cit., 582. See also Martin O’Neill, ‘Philosophy and Public Policy after Piketty’, Journal of Political Philosophy, 25.3 (2017), 343–375, esp. 361–5; Martin O’Neill, ‘James Meade and Predistribution: 50 Years Before his Time’, Policy Network: Classics of Social Democratic Thought, 2015, available at: . 39 Meade, op. cit., 35–7. 40 Meade, op. cit., 40–76. See also Martin O’Neill and Stuart White, ‘James Meade, Public Ownership, and the Idea of a Citizens’ Trust’, International Journal of Public Policy, 15 (1–2), 2019, 21–37. Anthony Atkinson, in his final book Inequality: What Can Be Done? (Harvard University Press, 2015), advocates a suite of egalitarian policies, including forms of ‘capital predistribution’ and the creation of a public ‘Investment Authority’, operating as a sovereign wealth fund, that can be read as an updated development of Meade’s pluralist egalitarian policy strategy. (Atkinson remarked to me that he wrote his book ‘with a copy of James’s book in front of me’ (personal correspondence, 4 January 2016)). 86 Martin O’Neill Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://web.archive.org/web/20170312125656/http://www.policy-network.net/pno_detail.aspx?ID=4909&title=James-Meade-and-predistribution-50-years-before-his-time https://web.archive.org/web/20170312125656/http://www.policy-network.net/pno_detail.aspx?ID=4909&title=James-Meade-and-predistribution-50-years-before-his-time https://web.archive.org/web/20170312125656/http://www.policy-network.net/pno_detail.aspx?ID=4909&title=James-Meade-and-predistribution-50-years-before-his-time https://web.archive.org/web/20170312125656/http://www.policy-network.net/pno_detail.aspx?ID=4909&title=James-Meade-and-predistribution-50-years-before-his-time https://web.archive.org/web/20170312125656/http://www.policy-network.net/pno_detail.aspx?ID=4909&title=James-Meade-and-predistribution-50-years-before-his-time https://www.cambridge.org/core In terms of getting to the normative heart of the predistributive ideal, though, what is most striking in Meade’s book is not so much the detail of his institutional proposals for ‘capital predistribu- tion’, as the content of his critique of existing forms of welfare state redistribution. He did not for a moment think that redistribution was unnecessary, or that predistributive measures should entirely replace traditional tax-and-spend or tax-and-transfer policies, but his worries about the limits of the familiar mid-twentieth century welfare state are powerfully expressed, and make a clear case for why it is that a concern only for the distribution of income cannot be sufficient to create an egalitarian economic settlement, and why ‘capital predistribution’ must be a necessary element of a just institu- tional structure. Here is the key passage: ‘Extreme inequalities in the ownership of property are in my view undesirable, quite apart from any inequalities of income which they may imply. A man with much property has great bar- gaining strength and a great sense of security, independence and freedom; and he enjoys these things not only vis-à-vis his proper- tyless fellow citizens but also vis-à-vis the public authorities. He can snap his fingers at those on whom he must rely for an income; for he can always live for a time on his capital. The propertyless man must continuously and without interruption acquire his income by working for an employer or by qualifying to receive it from a public authority. An unequal distribution of property means an unequal distribution of power and status even if it is pre- vented from causing too unequal a distribution of income’.41 The predistributive ideal involves seeing that individuals who sell their labour within the market need to be given (a) more equal bargaining power within the labour market, and (b) greater security, independence and freedom outside the labour market. Significantly, these goods have to be secured against both other people and against the state. And ul- timately these goals are best understood with regard to our underlying egalitarian interest in social relations of status and power. 9. Conclusion: Power, Predistribution, and Social Justice Predistribution is, one might say, the name for the broad set of egali- tarian economic policies justified by a conception of egalitarian com- mitment that goes beyond a concern only with the distribution of 41 Meade op. cit., 38–9. 87 Power, Predistribution, and Social Justice Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core goods and money, but which is centrally concerned with status and power in economic outcomes. There is, then, a clear sense in which the idea of predistribution has an internal connection to ideas of social egalitarianism, projected into the economic domain, embody- ing the ambition to think about economic policy in a way that goes beyond what Iris Marion Young has called ‘the distributive para- digm’.42 The point of predistributive policies is to shape the character of economic relationships, seen as sites for the exercise of power, and this therefore runs beyond a concern only with final distributive results. The twin egalitarian aims of such policies are dispersing power within markets, and making individuals less dependent on market outcomes in the first place. These twin aims are closely related, and can often be achieved together. It is a familiar objection directed at advocates of a political focus on predistribution, that even effective policies of predistribution would not eradicate the need for forms of redistribution, both in the form of direct cash transfers, and in the form of indirect transfers through the provision of public services funded through taxation. Obviously, the advocate of predistribution should have no argument with this objec- tion, not least because, as we have seen in sections 4–6 above, such redistributive policies frequently have a distinctively predistributive justification. Moving away from the Hacker-type view that sees predistribution as a kind of policy as opposed to a kind of aim or goal, or valuable effect, helps to forestall this kind of unilluminating disagreement between advocates of predistribution and their oppo- nents. Moreover, it should be no part of advocating predistributive public policies to think that there might not also be a justification for transfers or public service provision that was based on purely re- distributive considerations – i.e. because one person or group is in need, or suffering some absolute level of privation, and the transfer from a relatively advantaged person or group would rectify this. After all, our concerns as egalitarians are complex, combining consid- eration of both how well each individual fares, and of the nature of the social relations between individuals.43 There may also be cases where purely redistributive aims could be most efficiently enacted by means of the kinds of policy mechanisms associated with predistribution. In many cases, the same policies might be favoured by progressives and 42 See Martin O’Neill, ‘What Should Egalitarians Believe?’ Philosophy & Public Affairs, 36.2, 2008, 119–56. On the idea of the “distributive para- digm”, see Iris M. Young, Justice and the Politics of Difference, 2nd edition, (Princeton University Press, 2011). 43 Scanlon, op. cit.; O’Neill, op. cit. 88 Martin O’Neill Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core egalitarians for both their redistributive and predistributive effects, operating at once but by means of distinct mechanisms. None of these cases would constitute an objection to either our characterisa- tion of the idea of predistribution, or to the claim that progressive or egalitarian politics should treat predistribution as a central priority. Some of the political attraction of predistribution to centre-left parties and politicians during the 2010s rested on the fact it looked like the route to a social democratic strategy for an age of austerity, in which government spending was to be severely curtailed. But taking seriously the state’s role in shaping markets, or in accentuating the power of the disadvantaged, is not, as we have seen, something that can be done in isolation from thinking about the role of public services, or the role of the tax system. So the hope that a commitment to predistribution might be an egali- tarian strategy ‘on the cheap’, or one which could somehow be pursued without political conflict with existing economic interests, is obviously an illusory one. This might also be thought to be a point that stands against Hacker’s ‘instrumental’ defence of the focus on predistribution – that is, against the hope that the pursuit of egalitarian strategies that did not involve standard forms of redistribution might be achieved without whipping up the usual kinds of reactionary political backlash that might be expected to be faced by projects of egalitarian transformation in the economy. What we have seen in the foregoing discussion is that there is unlikely to be a way of achieving the aims of predistribution without significant changes both to labour regulation and to the fiscal system, involving in particular changes to the taxation of wealth and inherit- ance. Such measures are unlikely to be uncontroversial, or free from political backlash, even if it is also true that some forms of predistribu- tive public policy could, if skilfully designed, be more likely, at least in some places and at some times, to fly under the ‘political radar’ of anti-progressive or anti-egalitarian political forces. Predistribution is a capacious idea. One might say that it is the name for a problem in egalitarian public policy: that is, how can we create an economy without objectionable inequalities in bargaining power, in which the status, standing and self-respect of each is protected? It is not the name for any particular solution to this pressing and difficult problem. Nevertheless, by taking seriously the idea of predistribution we open up an important agenda for thinking about egalitarian public policy, and pursing the twin aims of equalizing market power and making individuals’ life chances less dependent on market 89 Power, Predistribution, and Social Justice Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core outcomes. Such an agenda emphasises the point that the character of economic relationships should be at the core of our thinking about social justice. For political philosophers, one central lesson is that, whereas the discipline has often thought a great deal about the assessment of dis- tributive outcomes, developing a cornucopia of principles for the normative assessment of all-things-considered final distributions, we need to think more about the detailed structure and texture of eco- nomic policy, and to give more consideration and attention to the social consequences both of particular policies and institutions, and to the interactions between them. We have an urgent collective goal in thinking not just about the distributive outcomes the economy produces, but in thinking more about the particular ways in which the economy can be shaped to disempower the privileged and to empower the disadvantaged.44 44 For helpful and stimulating comments and questions, I am grateful to audiences at the McCoy Family Center for Ethics in Society at Stanford University, at the Center for Ethics and Public Affairs at Tulane University, at the Harvard-Fudan-NYUAD Conference on Justice at Fudan University, Shanghai, at the Social Justice Centre at Concordia University, at the Universities of Jerusalem, Belgrade, Minho, and Sydney, and at McGill University, UCL, and the Universidad de Chile. I am also grateful to the Fabian Society, the Friedrich-Ebert-Stiftung of the German Social Democratic Party, and the Chifley Research Foundation of the Australian Labor Party for opportunities to discuss ideas of predistribution with political audiences. Thanks in particular to Pablo Aguayo Westwood, Daniel Attas, Tongdong Bai, Juliana Bidadanure, Jim Chalmers, Lindsey Chambers, Prithviraj Datta, Avner de-Shalit, Patrick Diamond, Peter Dietsch, Steven Durlauf, Bela Egyed, Marc Fleurbaey, Pablo Gilabert, Joe Guinan, Jacob Hacker, Louis-Philippe Hodgson, Ben Jackson, James Johnson, Liam Kennedy, Hélène Landemore, Ben Laurence, Ted Lechterman, Dominique Leydet, Désirée Lim, Fernando Lizárraga, Rocío Lorca Ferreccio, Roberto Merrill, Henning Meyer, Ed Miliband, Oded Na’aman, Dai Oba, Kristi Olson, Rachel Reeves, Jonathan Riley, Mathias Risse, T. M. Scanlon, Shlomi Segall, Nicole Selamé Glena, Ania Skrzypek, Lucas Stanczyk, Isaac Stanley, Christine Sypnowich, Alan Thomas, Isabella Trifan, Laura Valentini, Daniel Weinstock, Stuart White, Karl Widerquist, Andrew Williams, and Bernardo Zacka for illuminating discus- sion of the issues with which this article is concerned. I also thank the journal’s anonymous referees for their extremely helpful suggestions. I am pleased to be able to acknowledge research support from the Independent Social Research Foundation (ISRF), in the form of a research fellowship on ‘Social Justice, Predistribution, and the Democratization of Capital’. 90 Martin O’Neill Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core MARTIN O’NEILL is Senior Lecturer in Political Philosophy in the Department of Philosophy at the University of York. He is the author, with Joe Guinan, of The Case for Community Wealth Building (Polity Press, 2019), and the editor of Taxation: Philosophical Perspectives (OUP, 2018) (with Shepley Orr), and Property-Owning Democracy: Rawls and Beyond (Wiley-Blackwell, 2012) (with Thad Williamson). He works on a number of issues at the intersection of political philosophy, political economy, and public policy. 91 Power, Predistribution, and Social Justice Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:25, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core Power, Predistribution, and Social Justice Abstract Introduction: Predistribution, Redistribution, and Social Justice The Recent Conceptual History of Predistribution: Jacob Hacker on the ‘Institutional Foundations of Middle-Class Democracy’ A Better Account of Predistribution? Tax-and-Spend vs Market-Shaping The Case of Ukania The Plot Thickens: the Predistributive Function of Public Services The Case of USania Power, Public Services, and a Pluralist Account of Predistribution The Predistributive Role of Taxation and Cash Transfers The Predistributive Case for Universal Basic Income Predistribution and Top-Rate Income Tax: the Piketty-Saez-Stantcheva Effect The Collapse of the Distinction between Redistribution and Predistribution? The Pre-History of Predistribution: James Meade on the Twin Aims of Predistribution Conclusion: Power, Predistribution, and Social Justice work_cm7tuq2w5rdtfnhak6s6lhpqfm ---- S0031819120000017jra 211..225 Justice and History SUSAN NEIMAN Abstract This article explores intergenerational justice and its connection to historic (in)just- ice and reparations. It includes both the post-war period, and the abolition of the transatlantic slave trade, as case studies. 1. Introduction My concern here is intergenerational justice, a topic which young climate activists have brought to our attention. We owe our children a world which they can decently inhabit. This is self-evident for those of us who have biological children, at least since the invention of re- liable birth control; having made a decision to bring children into the world, we are responsible for making that world as decent as possible. Our possibilities are limited, as those of us who are parents painfully know, yet it is always in our power to make the world somewhat better or worse. Yet even those who never become parents have a responsi- bility to future generations, and not simply because future genera- tions should be counted in whatever calculations we make when considering the impact of our actions on others. It’s even more im- portant to focus on the specific fact of human being: we are animals who are part of a chain on which our existence rests. I’m inclined to think we owe a debt to the world for the gift of living in it; that making some contribution to the world that sustains us is incumbent on us all. Gratitude is a virtue, though it’s seldom explored. But even if you don’t accept a positive duty to pay something in return for the gift of life itself, I hope you’ll agree that making the world worse is an act of base ingratitude. Apres moi le deluge is an expression that became infamous for a reason. 2. Historic injustice My focus here, however, is our attitude to past generations who have made the world worse. Whether you focus on slavery or colonialism, arms races or global inequality, all of us were thrown into a world so problematic that fulfilling our obligations to the next generation by 211 doi:10.1017/S0031819120000017 © The Royal Institute of Philosophy, 2020 Philosophy 95 2020 Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core contributing to cleaning it up is an overwhelming task. Yet by virtue of the same chain that binds us to future generations, we have some relation to the sins of our fathers. We are not only animals who form part of a biological chain; we are animals who would perish without the care our parents provide in the first two years of life. Our parents’ care in turn is embedded and sustained in a web of social structures for which they may have limited responsibility, but without which they could not function: things as simple as water supplies and grocery stores, and as complex as government. I want to explore these questions by moving from the abstract to the particular, and looking at two cases I have studied closely for the past four years. While I think the claims I make can be extended to others, I believe that moral as well as legal responsibility must be grounded in particular historical details, so I will only gesture, in closing, at wider applications. Germans like long compound words, and they’ve invented one that has no equivalent in any other language: Vergangenheitsaufarbeitung. There are variations on the term in German, but I use this one – working off the past – because it implies that the past can, and should, be worked off in the way you work off a debt. It also implies that, for all but the very wealthy, debts must be worked-off slowly and incrementally, like mortgages. Unless you’re a billionaire, a one-off payment is rarely enough. Beginning in the ‘60s, a majority – or at least a very loud minority – of educated young Germans insisted that they, and their nation, needed to work-off the Nazi past. This was not a popular position, and most people outside Germany are shocked to learn that, for decades after the war, most West Germans did not feel the need to atone, or work-off anything at all. In fact, they saw themselves as the war’s worst victims. After all, their cities had been reduced to rubble, their territory dismembered, 7 million of their citizens killed; millions of men who survived were prisoners of war, humiliated by those they’d despised and sought to conquer. The first postwar years were marked by hunger and cold so intense that trees which had lined city streets for a hundred years were felled to keep their residents from freezing to death. And on top of it all, the occupiers of the two nations they most detested – the sub- human Russians and the vulgar Yankees – were insisting the war was their fault? It’s easy for even good historians like the former British Museum director Neal MacGregor to miss the undertone of self-pity that permeated postwar Germany. That’s partly because most Germans found it so obvious they didn’t bother to state it, and partly because the one picture of postwar Germany that captured international attention was the one we wanted to see: Willy Brandt on 212 Susan Neiman Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core his knees before the Warsaw Ghetto memorial. We did not know that Brandt’s gesture was unique. Brandt himself had done nothing for which he needed to repent; the committed Social Democrat fled Germany for Norway a few months after the Nazis took power. We did not know that this act, which made him a Good German in the eyes of the world, made him a Bad German in the eyes of the Christian Democrats. The most powerful party in Germany had no qualms about using Brandt’s self-imposed exile as a campaign slogan against him: ‘What was Herr Brandt doing abroad for twelve years?’ Still, when he became chancellor, Brandt felt he had a respon- sibility to atone for the crimes of the nation he represented. The spon- taneous act of kneeling, admired by other nations, was one reason his tenure as chancellor was cut short, though not the official reason. In 1970, most of West Germany saw no need for repentance, and cer- tainly no submissive gesture before the Slavs, who had never been viewed as a nation of equals. Far more typical of German leaders was the Christian Democrat Helmut Kohl, who famously insisted that he benefited from the ‘mercy of a late birth’.1 No sane person could ascribe personal respon- sibility to someone, like Kohl, who was three years old when the Nazis took power. For him and his contemporaries, therefore, the slate was wiped clean, and he could represent a new Germany unen- cumbered by its past. When he argued this in 1983, Kohl was so sharply criticized for the expression that he took it back seven years later, though his weak- kneed attempt to explain his earlier use of it convinced no one. For a change in consciousness, begun in the ‘60s, had begun to take hold among Germans who recognized the slate would never be clean unless they scrubbed harder. If you think this is overworking a metaphor, you should know that for decades, those who advocated working-off-the-past were called Nestbeschmützer, people who dirty their own nests. The Nestbeschmützer replied that the dirt was already there, stinking to high heaven, and could no longer be swept under the carpet. Those who have been to Berlin have probably seen the Holocaust memorial, a monument the size of four football fields placed next to Brandenburg Gate, which is the symbolic center of reunited Germany. One of the leaders of Germany’s new rightwing party, the AfD, complained that no other nation in the world has planted a monument of shame in the heart of its capitol. He is right to say 1 Hans Peter Schwarz, Helmut Kohl. Eine politische Biographie (Munich: Deutsche Verlags-Anstalt, 2012). 213 Justice and History Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core that no other nation has done it, wrong to complain about that. Germany’s decision to remember its criminal past should be a matter for precarious pride; the shame lies in the crimes, not the marking of them. This is now a consensus, though it’s a consensus the radical right is working to undermine. What I want to emphasize is how hard that consensus was to achieve, pace Willy Brandt. It took decades of struggle, often interge- nerational struggle, to force changes in notions of citizenship, govern- mental policies, educational systems and physical iconography. It’s a struggle that was often personally wrenching, because the insistence on facing one’s parents’ crimes seemed to conflict with the duty to respect your parents simply in virtue of the fact that they are your parents. Of course cultures differ widely in their views of the scope of that duty. Traditional cultures extend it to respecting your parents’ wishes for your own life, what profession you should enter or what person you should marry. But all cultures presuppose some respect for your parents simply because parenting – at its most basic, keeping small helpless creatures alive until they can live on their own – is bloody hard work. It would be even harder without the presumption that respect and gratitude are owed to the person or persons who do that work. In extreme cases of abuse – think of incest or hard violence – parents may forfeit their right to be re- spected. Extreme cases. So what if your parents were Nazis? This was the dilemma faced by most thoughtful Germans of my generation, give or take a decade. Dates mattered, as did exact biog- raphies. Those whose fathers were drafted, but served as medical or- derlies, had the easiest time of it. Some, like the son of Hans Frank, the high Nazi official who governed most of German-occupied Poland, has written about privately celebrating the date of his father’s execution. One can hardly imagine the clashes in this man’s soul, torn between the duty to respect and mourn the people who sired us, and the knowledge that his father truly was one man who could not claim to be only following orders. He gave them. But even those whose parents were far less culpable felt contaminated by their parents’ sins. Only those who truly resisted Nazi crimes were not complicit in them – and most of those who truly resisted were dead. It’s significant that many West Germans of that generation chose not to have children themselves, largely because their notions of family and authority, respect and responsibility had become so con- flicted. Some Germans, such as Bernhard Schlink, author of the dreadful albeit bestselling novel The Reader, even argued that the only way a German can escape her Nazi parents’ guilt is to break 214 Susan Neiman Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core with them entirely.2 Many did. In order to restore some sense of health to the chain that binds parents and children, working-off their parents’ debts was unavoidable. Most states require that debts be paid before deceased persons’ assets are distributed to heirs. It’s a legal obligation you can only avoid by refusing to accept an inherit- ance at all, which isn’t even possible in all cases. This aspect of law is based on intuitions about fairness: you have no right to enjoy the ben- efits of an inheritance and reject its liabilities. Unlike personal prop- erty, historical debt can rarely be quantified. Yet the intuition embodied in the law is one we are right to preserve. Our relation to our nations is not, of course, exactly analogous to our relation to our parents, but the analogy is strong enough to be useful. We all benefit from inheritances we did not ask for, and can only partially reject, if we choose. These include, most crucially, being born into a particular culture, with all the history and social structures that implies. The difference between being born in Scotland and being born in Somalia makes all the difference in the world, and a Scot who moves to Somalia will see that more clearly, not less so. Seeing clearly can involve seeing reasons for pride in one’s own culture as well as shame for its failures. But there’s a reason why the joke about what makes an Austrian is so bitterly funny. ‘An Austrian is someone who tries to convince you that Hitler is from Germany and Beethoven from Vienna’. Unlike Hitler’s birthplace Austria, where support for the Nazis was even stronger, Germany went through a decades-long process which involved many elements. One I want to turn to now was the payment of reparations. 3. Reparations No material payment can compensate for the suffering inflicted by slavery. No one who has read a thorough description of slavery, in Auschwitz or Alabama, would prefer it – no matter the compensation – to never having been enslaved at all. The Austrian Jewish philoso- pher and writer Jean Améry, who was imprisoned in Auschwitz for two years, wrote that the only thing that could truly make up for those crimes would be turning back time and undoing them.3 The 2 Bernhard Schlink, The Reader, (Vintage International, 1995). 3 Jean Améry, At The Mind’s Limits: Contemplations by a Survivor on Auschwitz and its Realities, Edited by: S. Rosenfeld and S. P. Rosenfeld, (London: Granta Books, 1966). 215 Justice and History Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core only way to solve the problem, he concluded, was ‘by permitting resentment to remain alive in the one camp and, aroused by it, self- mistrust in the other’. If this took place, Germans would have inte- grated Auschwitz into their natural history rather than allowing it to be neutralized by time. Améry himself, a man of exquisite moral sensibility, did not apply for the reparations he was owed, despite the fact that his material situ- ation after the Liberation was anything but solid. In fact, the roughly 80 billion marks that West Germany paid to Holocaust victims were only accompanied by a half-hearted apology wrested from Adenauer by the Israelis, who virtually wrote it. (The reparations paid by East Germany to Poland and the Soviet Union were forced, though it is telling that with a resolutely anti-fascist government in power, many East Germans thought the reparations were fair.) In his first speech to parliament in 1949, Adenauer had lamented the wartime suffering of a long list of Germans – those who lost their homes to an- nexation or bombing, those interned in POW camps, those who were widowed or crippled. Before entering into talks about concrete sums, therefore, Israel insisted that Adenauer make a formal statement to parliament admitting German culpability for crimes against the Jewish people. The Jews wanted more acknowledgment of guilt, the Germans wanted less, and what emerged was a compromise. Still, the apology was historic, as were the payment of reparations for it. In making those payments, however, Adenauer’s government made an implicit bargain: in paying money to our victims we have fin- ished the process of working-off-our past. We can turn our faces away from the shameful pages of our history, make no attempt to remove former Nazis from our government, our schools, or our cultural insti- tutions, and consider accounts settled. It’s important that almost 50 years after Adenauer’s agreement, the newly elected Social Democratic/Green government created a foundation, consisting of both government and industry, that not only paid reparations for the slave laborers who had not yet been compensated, mostly because they lived in Eastern Europe. The foundation also set aside funds for projects to remember the past in Eastern Europe, and called itself Memory, Responsibility and Future. In 1966, Améry quoted a man who tells him the reparations payments mean that Germans bear the Jews no grudges. Under those circumstances, it’s understandable that he refused to take those payments; he was waiting for the genuine remorse that did not come until after he died by his own hand. Half a century after Améry book was published, it would be hard to find a German today who does not wish to turn time around and 216 Susan Neiman Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core undo Nazi crimes – even if only to avoid the decades of national shame that followed. The remorse is genuine. But if reparations without apology may be blind, apologies without reparations may be empty. The U.S. Congress did not even issue an apology for slavery until 2008. The discussion about reparations for slavery, which had been held on and off since the ‘60s, was given new life with an essay by the writer Ta-Nehisi Coates. As he rightly wrote, ‘the idea of repara- tions is frightening not simply because we might lack the ability to pay. The idea of reparations threatens something much deeper – America’s heritage, history, and standing in the world’.4 Those who oppose American reparations for slavery have seldom responded directly to that claim, but they’re quick to dismiss the German precedent by pointing out the differences between the two cases. Their arguments turn on the justice as well as the difficulty of assessing claims made on the basis of a crime that occurred genera- tions ago. Any serious discussion of American reparations for slavery must acknowledge two facts: 1. America’s wealth is intrinsically bound up with profits from slavery, from the plantations of the South to the factories of the North. Earlier histories of slavery portrayed it as a premodern, agrarian insti- tution. Recent scholarship has shown, however, that slavery was a major engine of the growth of the modern American and British economies. Cotton was as central to the nineteenth-century economy as oil is to the economy today. It wasn’t just the raw material for the nineteenth century’s most successful industry, the textile mills that were as profitable in Manchester, New Hampshire, as in Manchester, England. Cotton also drove increasing demand for iron goods, rope, furniture, and shoes. Apart from the products pro- duced by their labor, enslaved people themselves made up 20 percent of America’s wealth. As cotton production boomed, the separation of enslaved families became central to the slave system. Slaves were torn from their families because they fetched twice as much in New Orleans as they did in Virginia. Less obvious but more insidious was the way that bonds using those slaves as collateral enriched inves- tors all over the world. The historian Edward Baptist showed that torture of slaves was not the product of accidental sadism nor even 4 Ta-Nehisi Coates, ‘The Case for Reparations’, The Atlantic (https:// www.theatlantic.com/magazine/archive/2014/06/the-case-for-reparations/ 361631/, 2014). 217 Justice and History Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.theatlantic.com/magazine/archive/2014/06/the-case-for-reparations/361631/, 2014 https://www.theatlantic.com/magazine/archive/2014/06/the-case-for-reparations/361631/, 2014 https://www.theatlantic.com/magazine/archive/2014/06/the-case-for-reparations/361631/, 2014 https://www.cambridge.org/core a matter of punishment for alleged infractions. It was a central factor of production, forcing enslaved men and women to labor at inhuman speeds. ‘The whip’, he concludes, ‘was as important to making cotton grow as sunshine and rain’.5 2. Chattel slavery was abolished in 1865, but it was replaced by other forms of subjugation that were not just a function of custom and prejudice but a matter of law. Long before the Civil War, some Quaker communities made mem- bership contingent on compensating one’s former slaves. Yale presi- dent Timothy Dwight wrote, ‘It is in vain to allege that our ancestors brought them hither, and not we … We inherit our ample patrimony with all its incumbrances, and are bound to pay the debts of our an- cestors … To give [slaves] liberty, and stop here, is to entail upon them a curse’. As the war drew to its bloody close, there was initial support for the idea that African Americans were owed some com- pensation for generations of forced labor, support that led to the initial declaration that each freedman would be offered forty acres of land and a mule, and almost a million acres of Southern land were set aside for this purpose. Had it been realized, it would have been an act of reparation for the thousands of acres those African Americans had worked, under the lash, without pay. Moreover, the vision of small, independent farmers exactly fit Jefferson’s concep- tion of the ideal conditions for a democratic republic. But Jefferson’s vision had been replaced by reveries of profit in the world cotton market. Both North and South preferred large planta- tions producing for export to self-sufficient small farmers. Moreover, President Andrew Johnson was keen on restoring the rights and properties of the Southern planters who’d always had his sympathy. Not half a year after Lincoln’s murder, Johnson over- turned every order that had granted land to freed people and returned it to the planters who had started the war. Both neoslavery and terror were instruments white Southerners used to wipe out the gains of Reconstruction. In the absence of federal troops and Northern engagement, Southern states fiercely en- forced the laws known as the Black Codes, which were largely suc- cessful attempts to evade the Thirteenth Amendment, which had 5 Edward Baptist, ‘Picking Up Cotton Under the Pushing System’, Slate (https://slate.com/human-interest/2015/08/slavery-under-the-pushing- system-why-systematic-violence-became-a-necessity.html, 2015). 218 Susan Neiman Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://slate.com/human-interest/2015/08/slavery-under-the-pushing-system-why-systematic-violence-became-a-necessity.html, 2015 https://slate.com/human-interest/2015/08/slavery-under-the-pushing-system-why-systematic-violence-became-a-necessity.html, 2015 https://www.cambridge.org/core outlawed slavery ‘except as punishment for a crime whereof the party shall have been duly convicted’. In the warped justice system of the postwar South, nothing was easier than inventing crimes and duly convicting African Americans of them. Most were arrested under de- liberately obscure vagrancy laws, according to which black persons unable to immediately prove they were currently employed by a white person could be charged, convicted, and sentenced to hard labor. Offenses such as spitting, selling produce after dark, walking next to a railroad, and talking loudly near a white woman could also result in prison terms. Historian Douglas Blackmon has shown that the system of neoslav- ery, was more brutal than the chattel slavery which preceded it. Under the old system, a chattel slave was the owner’s property. Having made a considerable investment in a black human being, the enslaver had an economic interest in preserving that investment by upholding minimal standards of nutrition and health. Under the new system, convicts were not owned but merely leased by state prisons to private corporations that mined coal, forged steel, or built bricks. In some Alabama prison camps the mortality rate was 40 percent. If a convict died from malnutrition, lashing, overwork, or disease, the corporation could always get another. The timing and scale of arrests were repeatedly correlated with the demand for cheap labor. Just before harvest time, for example, the number of arrests increased dramatically. Focusing on such policies, and the less brutal but still damaging ones that replaced them in the early 20th century, removes the first ob- jection raised concerning reparations for African Americans: How can anyone determine to whom reparations are owed? Here there’s no need to trace lines back to the mid-19th century. If it can be proved that legal measures created to subjugate African Americans persisted a century after slavery was abolished, the debt that was owed to enslaved people should be paid to their heirs. The evidence for those claims was overlooked only because, for too many Americans, the period between the Emancipation Proclamation and the Montgomery bus boycott is simply blank. Recent research allows us to fill in that blank. Reparations, Coates argued, would be the full acceptance of our collective biography and its consequences. ‘More important than any single check cut to any African American, the payment of repara- tions would represent America’s maturation out of the childhood myth of its innocence into a wisdom worthy of its founders’.6 From 6 Op. cit. note 4. 219 Justice and History Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core myth to wisdom: it’s a matter of growing up. I have argued elsewhere that a healthy adult relationship to your nation is like a healthy rela- tionship to your parents. As children, we tend to accept whatever they tell and give us; what other choice do we have? That lack of choice often leads us, in adolescence, to reject our parents’ world(s) entirely. A grownup relationship to your parents involves sifting through all the things they taught you and deciding what you want to keep as your own, and pass on to further generations, and what you’d rather reject. We need to treat our national and cultural histories similarly. Another argument against reparations is that they support a culture of victimhood that is unhealthy for all. As I’ve argued elsewhere, a culture of victimhood is indeed problematic. But those objections can become reasons to support reparations, as long as that support is properly grounded. Proper grounding would come with an apology and a full description of the wrong that was done. Unlike welfare or affirmative action, reparations would be seen as a straight- forward payment for an overdue debt. If our forebears failed to pay it, the responsibility to do so devolves on those of us who benefit from that failure, whether the benefits come directly from wealth or other privileges gained from belonging to the white majority of a powerful nation. Other means of addressing racial inequality have proved problematic. First, it’s not clear that affirmative action pro- grams help those most in need of support. Giving preference in edu- cation or employment to members of disempowered groups so long as it’s arguable they are equally qualified necessarily benefits the best qualified members of those groups, not those who need basic remed- ial education and other forms of support. Moreover, even when they have been faithfully applied, those programs can harm even those they are designed to benefit. suspicion infects relationships between members of different groups, feeding resentment on one side and self-doubt on the other. Honest payment of a debt that both parties recognize avoids this. Sidestepping concepts like ‘trauma’ and ‘victim’, reparations are supported by simpler ideas of justice. And to those who argue that reparations look backward, while politics should look to the future, one simply has to look at contemporary United States and Britain to see how well ignoring the past has worked. Others have argued that people whose ancestors were slaveholders might be liable for reparations, but those who held no slaves are not. Now most nonblack Americans are descended from people who came to the country in the waves of immigration that began after the Civil War. Nevertheless, in taking on the benefits of citizenship, they took 220 Susan Neiman Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core on its responsibilities as well. It’s usually only first-generation immi- grants who consciously take on those responsibilities – if people fleeing poverty, or worse, reflect on such responsibilities at all. Most of us are citizens without active consent. We had no choice about the place where our mothers happened to give birth, and we could not possibly consent to it – any more than we could consent to being born. Some of the most important things that determine our lives are entirely contingent, in ways that can be tragic or wonder- ful. We may begin by understanding our debts to the past by analogy with familial inheritances, but our responsibility to our nation’s past is political. To be a citizen is not merely to take responsibility for your country’s history since the moment you, or your ancestors, claimed its citizenship. Political identity cannot merely be a matter of acquir- ing the benefits that accrue to possessing one passport or another. Though the individuals responsible for slavery and all that followed are long gone, many of the corporate entities, public and private, that legalized and profited from slavery still exist. So do descendants of those who still suffer discrimination because they are part of a group that was brought to America in chains. So long as they live in a society built on injustice, even those who have not incurred guilt are responsible for correcting it. A final objection is that the payment of reparations is decisive; a majority of white Americans and Britons are against it. (Though support for reparations have increased, in the US, in the past few years, as consciousness of the history of neoslavery has increased.) More importantly: So were the vast majority of Germans in the 1950s. Adenauer could muster the votes in favor of reparations only by going outside his own conservative Christian Democratic Union and appealing to the Social Democrats. Outside pressure from the United States played a central role in persuading Adenauer that sig- nificant reparations were necessary to gain readmission to what was called the family of civilized nations. Some have suggested solving problems of racial inequality by insisting on social programs that would benefit all, as a way of widening general support. And as a Social Democrat, or democratic socialist, I am certainly in favor of systems that guarantee the right to health care, education, parental leave, fair working conditions, and yes, even paid vacation as a matter of right, not benefit. Still I want to propose a thought experiment: what if all those were guar- anteed, as human rights, to every citizen. Would descendants of slaves be owed something more? Contrast this question with another. A Holocaust survivor who chose to remain in Germany after the war – and some did – would 221 Justice and History Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core receive the same palette of social services as her ex-Nazi neighbors. Before Germany’s Economic Miracle, those services were limited, but as the 1960s brought prosperity, their range expanded. Would we think justice served if the survivor were guaranteed the same eco- nomic and social rights as the rest of the nation, or would we think she deserved something more for the pain and terror most of the nation inflicted on her? No compensation could redeem the loss of her parents or children. Still, something more than regular social ser- vices – regarded as a right for everyone – seems owed to her for the wrong she suffered. Something more than words of apology. Nor does it matter whether the wrong was intentional. The histor- ian Isaac Deutscher illustrated this with a parable: suppose a man jumped from a burning house in which many of his family had died, and hit a passing stranger, breaking her arms and legs in falling. If both people were reasonable, they would not become enemies. The jumper would try to console and compensate the inno- cent stranger, who would understand that she was a victim of acciden- tal circumstance. If they were irrational, they will be caught in an endless cycle of resentment, fear, and revenge. Deutscher used this parable to describe the justified claims of Israeli Jews and Palestinians in 1967, but it can be applied to many cases. To this day, Israel has refused to recognize the justice of Palestinian claims that began when Jews fled a burning Europe, and those claims have only become more valid under the long occupation. All the more urgent are the claims of the victims of American racism, whose per- petrators can hardly be compared with someone escaping a burning home. How far back do our obligations extend? Noting British prime minister Tony Blair’s apology for injustices committed against the Irish a century earlier, the author Robert Penn Warren asked if an apology should extend to Oliver Cromwell, who devastated Ireland in the seventeenth century. Penn Warren thought he was showing the absurdity of demands for historical justice, but the question is worth taking seriously. At the close of the twentieth century, the punk group The Pogues sang A curse upon you Oliver Cromwell You who raped our Motherland and hoped he was burning in hell as they sang it. As long as public memory is seething over unacknowledged injustice, the heirs of those who wreaked it should, at the least, acknowledge it. The philosopher Janna Thompson has argued that obligations to right historical wrongs persist indefinitely, if not eternally. She 222 Susan Neiman Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core believes that keeping transgenerational commitments, implicit or not, is the central moral and political good that gives nations the basis for trust. Philosophical theories of reparations depend on two different arguments: one emphasizing historical obligations, the other present needs. The case for American reparations for slavery can be made on both grounds – the historical obligation arising from the evil of slavery, as well as the present economic condition of most of its descendants. To those claims Thompson adds a third: ‘Maintaining a political society capable of acting justly in a world of nations depends essentially on a moral practice that requires each generation of citizens to take responsibility for keeping the commit- ments of its predecessors and repairing their injustice’.7 This way of grounding an obligation for reparations requires no appeal to guilt for the sins of long-dead ancestors, nor does it appeal to obliga- tions automatically conferred by citizenship. It can be applied very widely, though determining the exact obligations must be decided case by case. Particular circumstances always matter. 4. Conclusion If there’s no algorithm that can calculate how far obligations may go back in time, there is also none that can determine how wide they may reach across space. The claim that the United States owes reparations for slavery has been followed by the argument that European nations owe reparations to the Caribbean community, where slavery was often even more brutal and devastating than it was in the American South. Given the importance of the slave trade, and the products of slavery, for building nineteenth-century Europe’s wealth, no further argument might be needed. But the Caribbean community is right to focus on one fact that’s particularly galling: after abolishing slavery in its colonies in 1833, Britain paid 20 million pounds to com- pensate former enslavers for the loss of what they considered their property. The amount, at the time, was 40 percent of annual govern- ment income and had to be financed by private loan. British taxpayers paid the interest on that debt until 2015. Opponents of reparations will blanch: the case I’ve sketched does imply that there is no honest way to resist claims for reparations on a global scale. The difficulty of figuring out how to allot what to whom is no excuse for refusing to try. It’s probably impossible to 7 Janna Thompson, Taking Responsibility for the Past: Reparation and Historical Justice (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2002). 223 Justice and History Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core calculate the amounts the United States owes to Native Americans, or European countries to their former colonies. Still, the U.S. could begin by restoring mineral rights on the reservations of the former, and Europeans by forgiving the debt of the latter. This could initiate the sort of cleansing Karl Jaspers thought necessary and inescapable for Germany in 1946. After reparations to Israel began, other Germans spoke of retrieving lost honor. Some have suggested that an apology for colonialism is more important than material compen- sation. The Indian politician and author Shashi Tharoor said that a symbolic payment of one pound a year would suffice as reparations for two hundred years of British rule in India. Reparations, he argued in a 2015 speech at the Oxford Union, are ‘not a tool to empower anybody, they are a tool for you to atone…The ability to ac- knowledge your wrong, to simply say sorry, will go a far, far longer way than some percentage of the GDP in the form of aid’.8 This is a remarkable statement, given Tharoor’s argument that Britain’s in- dustrial revolution was premised on the destruction of India’s pre- colonial economy; as in many other colonies, what had been a self-sufficient system was turned into a source of raw material, often through barbaric means. An apology for those abuses would, at the least, acknowledge that foreign aid to developing countries – of which European countries contribute twice as much, relative to GDP, as the United States – is a matter of obligation, not generosity. It might even restrain the development of the new forms of neo-colo- nialism that many corporations practice today. But for the reasons just sketched, I don’t believe that acknowledgment is enough. Opponents of reparations counter that the cost of all that debt would be impossible to raise, which makes them reluctant to even acknowledge it. Proposals to repair massive injustice are inevitably met with the claim that there isn’t enough money in the world to do so. Several tax- ation policies that might finance reparations have been proposed, but if we are serious about seeking the means to restore justice, the real elephant in the room is the arms industry. Too many of us continue to ignore it. If no one ever produced or profited from another weapon again, we’d still have enough to defend (or kill) ourselves many times over. As in the fable of the emperor’s new clothes, it takes a child to point out the obvious. When Malala Yousefzai’s life was threatened for demanding girls’ rights to education, the world took notice, and 8 See: https://www.independent.co.uk/news/uk/home-news/dr-shashi- tharoor-tells-the-oxford-union-why-britain-owes-reparations-for-colonising- india-in-viral-10407997.html. 224 Susan Neiman Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.independent.co.uk/news/uk/home-news/dr-shashi-tharoor-tells-the-oxford-union-why-britain-owes-reparations-for-colonising-india-in-viral-10407997.html https://www.independent.co.uk/news/uk/home-news/dr-shashi-tharoor-tells-the-oxford-union-why-britain-owes-reparations-for-colonising-india-in-viral-10407997.html https://www.independent.co.uk/news/uk/home-news/dr-shashi-tharoor-tells-the-oxford-union-why-britain-owes-reparations-for-colonising-india-in-viral-10407997.html https://www.cambridge.org/core she became the youngest person ever to receive the Nobel Peace Prize. Very little attention was paid a few years later, when she used her edu- cation to argue that all children have a right to twelve years of free education – and that this could be paid for by cutting military spend- ing for just eight days every year. That fact, confirmed for me by a Nobel laureate in economics, received little attention because we have no idea what to do with it. If there were an international vote about priorities, a motion to replace military spending with education – at least for eight days – would surely win hands down. We do not even know what structures would frame such a decision process.9 SUSAN NEIMAN (sneiman@einsteinforum.de) is director of the Einstein Forum. Born in Atlanta, Georgia, Neiman studied philosophy at Harvard and the Free University of Berlin. She was professor of philosophy at Yale University and Tel Aviv University before coming to the Einstein Forum in 2000. Her works include Slow Fire: Jewish Notes from Berlin, The Unity of Reason: Rereading Kant, Evil in Modern Thought, Moral Clarity: A Guide for Grown-up Idealists, Why Grow Up? Subversive Thoughts for an Infantile Age, and Learning from the Germans: Race and the Memory of Evil. 9 This paper was originally delivered as the 2019 Royal Institute of Philosophy/Royal Society of Edinburgh Lecture, on Monday 25 November. 225 Justice and History Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:39, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. mailto:sneiman@einsteinforum.de https://www.cambridge.org/core Justice and History Abstract Introduction Historic injustice Reparations America's wealth is intrinsically bound up with profits from slavery, from the plantations of the South to the factories of the North. Chattel slavery was abolished in 1865, but it was replaced by other forms of subjugation that were not just a function of custom and prejudice but a matter of law. Conclusion work_cm7zf66ngjdybed6irafx4efke ---- 157 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. La justice administrative au brésil A justiça administrativa no brasil Ricardo Perlingeiro 1 RÉSUMÉ: Il s’agit d’une analyse descriptive de certains aspects du système de justice administrative brésilien, quant à la procédure administrative, au système judiciaire et à la procédure juridictionnelle, identifiant leurs aspects positifs et négatifs, de façon à servir de base à une étude comparée au regard des systèmes qui l’ont influencé, en Europe continentale et aux USA, et de ceux influencés par ces derniers en Ibéro-Amérique. MOTS-CLÉS: Procès équitable - Tribunal administratif - Droit compare. RESUMO: O texto contém uma análise descritiva de alguns aspectos do sistema de justiça administrativa brasileiro, quanto ao procedimento administrativo, sistema judiciário e processo judicial, identificando seus pontos positivos e negativos, de modo a servir de base para uma investigação comparada em face de sistemas que o influenciaram, na Europa continental e nos EUA, e daqueles que, por estes, foram igualmente influenciados no âmbito da Ibero-América. PALAVRAS-CHAVE: Processo justo – Tribunal administrativa – Direito comparado. 1 Juge fédéral de Rio de Janeiro. Professeur à l'université Estácio de Sá et à l'université fédérale Fluminense. 158 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. INTRODUCTION Il convient d’amorcer un dialogue entre les systèmes brésilien et français en ce qui concerne le contentieux administratif. En effet, dans ce domaine, la production scientifique comparée entre le Brésil et la France est proportionnellement minime, bien que le modèle brésilien de “justice administrative”, ait subi dans le passé l’influence de la France, avec son système dualiste de juridiction. En outre, même après que le modèle juridictionnel français ait succombé au Brésil, lors de l’instauration de la République, en 1891, remplacé par le modèle de juridiction unique, le droit administratif matériel français est encore une des sources d’inspiration de la doctrine et de la législation brésiliennes. 2 À ce propos, la présente étude a pour but de procéder à une analyse descriptive et ponctuelle du système de justice administrative brésilien, en ce qui concerne la procédure administrative non contentieuse l’organisation et la procédure juridictionnelle, en en relevant certains aspects positifs et négatifs, à partir des principes d’État de Droit et de protection juridictionnelle effective, tels que concrétisés par les matrices du droit administratif en Europe3 et de leur reflet dans certains modèles ibéro-américains, de façon à élaborer une étude comparée de ces systèmes avec le système français. Dans un premier temps, il convient de déterminer la portée et le contexte de la terminologie utilisée. L’expression “contentieux administratif” se rapporte aux réclamations ou aux contestations d’un particulier vis à vis des actes d’une autorité administrative. L’expression “juridiction administrative” sert à désigner la prestation juridictionnelle destinée à la résolution d’un litige administratif, et “justice administrative”, désigne les organes de l’État responsables de rendre la justice.4 2 RECOURS ADMINISTRATIF PRÉALABLE 2 PERLINGEIRO, Ricardo; BLANKE, Hermann-Josef; SOMMERMANN, Karl-Peter (Coords.). Código de jurisdição administrativa: o modelo alemão. Rio de Janeiro: Renovar, 2009. p. 65. 3 O direito francês, o direito inglês e o direito alemão (FROMONT, Michel. Droit administratif des Etats européens. Paris: PUF, 2006. p. 7). 4 UNIVERSITÉ FÉDÉRALE FLUMINENSE. Centre des Sciences du Pouvoir Judiciaire. Projeto Acadêmico do Programa de Pós-Graduação Justiça Administrativa – PPGJA-UFF. Niterói, 2008. 159 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. En principe, dans un État de Droit, le contentieux administratif doit être confié exclusivement à une juridiction; cependant, il est admis que le conflit soit préalablement soumis à l’Administration Publique elle-même, sans que, néanmoins, cela constitue une exception au principe d’accès à la justice (subordination de l’Administration au juge).5 Nous faisons ici référence à la technique des autorités administratives supérieures auprès desquelles les intéressés, lorsqu’ils sont contrariés par l’Administration, interjettent un recours non contentieux devant l’autorité administrative hiérarchiquement supérieure, comme cela se trouve dans la plupart des systèmes, et de façon encore plus marquante en Allemagne, où les recours ont un effet suspensif automatique et constituent une condition sine qua non à l’introduction d’une action juridictionnelle.6 Je me réfère également à la technique des Autorités Administratives Indépendantes où les recours non contentieux sont jugés par des agents publics qui, en dépit du fait d’être nommés directement par des membres du premier échelon de l’Administration, exercent leurs fonctions de façon indépendante, n’étant pas subordonnés hiérarchiquement, à la différence des “tribunaux administratifs” anglais, des “commissions de recours” suisses et des “chambres administratives” en Autriche.7 Au Brésil, ces deux techniques peuvent être observées et, respectant le principe de la protection juridictionnelle effective, elles constituent une possibilité pour les intéressés qui, même une fois exercée, n’exclut pas l’introduction simultanée d'actions visant à obtenir des mesures d’urgence. Le recours devant une autorité administrative supérieure, qui ne doit pas être confondu avec la réclamation préalable (très souvent indispensable à la constitution même du droit subjectif), est prévu dans la législation brésilienne de procédure administrative.8 Le recours devant une autorité administrative indépendante est semblable, par exemple, aux recours intentés devant le Conseil Administratif des Ressources Fiscales (CARF),9 les agences régulatrices,10 les Tribunaux des Comptes11 et, pourquoi pas, devant le Conseil National de Justice (CNJ).12 5 FROMONT, op. cit., p. 112-119. 6 Verwaltungsgerichtsordnung/VwGO (Code de Juridiction Administrative – Loi du 21 janvier 1960), §§ 68, 80. 7 FROMONT, op. cit. 8 Loi nº 9.784, du 29 janvier 1999, art. 56.. 9 Loi nº 11.941, du 27 mai 2009. 10Agence Nationale pour l’Aviation Civile – ANAC (Loi nº 11.182, du 27 septembre 2005); Agence Nationale des Eaux – ANA (Loi nº 9.984, du 17 juillet 2000); Agence Nationale pour l’Énergie Électrique – ANEEL (Loi nº 9.427, du 26 décembre 1996); Agence Nationale pour le Pétrole, le Gaz Naturel et les Bicombustibles – ANP (Loi nº 9.478, du 6 août 1997; Loi nº 9.990, du 21 juillet 2000; Loi nº 12.351, du 22 décembre 2010); Agence Nationale pour la Santé Supplémentaire – ANS (Loi nº 9.961, du 28 janvier 2000); Agence Nationale pour les Transports Terrestres – ANTT (Loi nº 10.233, du 5 juin 2001); Agence Nationale pour la Vigilance Sanitaire – ANVISA (Loi nº 9.782, du 26 janvier 1999). 160 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. 3 ORGANISATION DE LA JURIDICTION ADMINISTRATIVE La juridiction administrative proprement dite, substantiellement indépendante de l’Administration, fait l’objet d’une organisation que l’on peut classifier comme suit: (1) juridiction administrative ayant à la fois un rôle consultatif et un rôle contentieux, comme en France,13 aux Pays-Bas,14 en Italie,15 en Grèce,16 en Belgique17 et en Colombie,18 dont les Conseils d’État ont simultanément une fonction de cour suprême et d’organe consultatif; (2) juridiction administrative constituant un ordre juridictionnel autonome, avec une cour suprême de droit public spécifiquement, ayant un rôle uniquement contentieux, comme en Allemagne,19 en Autriche,20 en Suède21 et au Portugal;22 (3) juridiction administrative autonome de 1o et 2o degrés dépendante cependant d’une cour suprême unique, qui soit non seulement de droit public mais aussi de droit privé, comme en Espagne,23 en Suisse,24 en Hongrie25 et au Mexique;26 (4) juridiction administrative “privée”, connue également sous le nom de “juridiction unique” ou “système moniste”, qui comprend droit public et droit privé, et qui est éventuellement dotée d’organes spécialisés en contentieux administratif, typique des 11 Tribunal des Comptes de l’Union – TCU (Loi nº 8.443, du 16 juillet 1992). 12 Loi nº 11.364, du 26 octobre 2006. 13 Code de Justice Administrative, R. 122-15, R. 122-18 e R. 122-20. 14 Wet van 9 maart 1962, op de Raad van State (Loi du 9 mars 1962), art. 1º. 15 Legge 27 aprile 1982, n. 186 (Loi nº 186, du 27 avril 1982). 16 Νομοθετικού διατάγματος [Ν] 170/1973 (Décret Législatif nº 170/1973, modifié par les Lois nº 702/1977 et nº 1.470/1984 et codifié par le Décret nº 18/1989). 17 Constitution Belge (1993. Texte coordonné le 17 février 1994), art. 160; Loi du 23 décembre 1946 – Loi du Conseil d’État de Belgique (Loi du 23 décembre 1946). 18 Constitución Política de Colombia (Constitution du 20 juillet 1991), art. 237; Ley nº 1.437, de 18 de enero de 2011. 19 Verwaltungsgerichtsordnung/VwGO (Code de Juridiction Administrative – Loi du 21 janvier 1960), §§ 49 et 50. 20 Bundes-Verfassungsgesetz (Constitution du 1o octobre 1920), art. 130, 1. 21 Författning 1974 (Constitution de 1974. Approuvée le 1o janvier 1975), art. 1º, Chapitre 11. 22 Constitution de la République Portugaise, du 2 avril 1976, art. 209, 1, b; Code de Procédure des Tribunaux Administratifs (Loi nº 4-A, du 19 février 2003). 23 Constitución Española, de 29 de diciembre de 1978, art. 106, 1. 24 Verfassung der Schweiz (Constitution approuvée par référendum le 12 mars 2000), art. 29 a, 191 et 191 b. 25 Bírósági szervezet szóló 1997 (Loi de l’Organisation Judiciaire de 1997). 26 Constitución Política de los Estados Unidos Mexicanos, de 5 de febrero de 1917, art. 94; Ley Orgánica del Tribunal Federal de Justicia Fiscal y Administrativa (Dernière réforme publiée le 3 juin 2011). 161 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. systèmes de common law, comme en Angleterre,27 en Irlande,28 au Danemark,29 mais également présents en Argentine,30 au Chili,31 au Costa Rica,32 au Pérou33 et au Venezuela.34 Curieusement, le droit brésilien connaît les quatre modalités d’organisation de la juridiction administrative. Avant la République on se rapprochait de la juridiction administrative avec des fonctions à la fois consultative et contentieuse, malgré le fait que le Conseil d’État de l’Empire ait été calqué sur la première version du Conseil d’État français, avec une “justice retenue” entre les mains de l’Empereur, sans fonctions réellement juridictionnelles ou déléguées.35 Ce n’est qu’avec la Constitution de 1891 que le droit brésilien a connu la juridiction administrative, mais, à cette époque, elle possédait des caractéristiques propres aux systèmes du common law, avec des tribunaux amenés à connaître autant du droit public que du droit privé. Ce système de “juridiction unique” qui prédomine encore aujourd’hui, contient un certain niveau de spécialisation en droit public, ainsi qu’il en est question dans les “Varas de Fazenda Pública” (Chambres des finances publiques), de première instance, et dans les « sections » ou “Chambres” au niveau des cours d’appel.36 En ce qui concerne la Justice Fédérale de 1º et 2º Degrés, qui comprend une juridiction administrative compétente pour l’Administration Publique fédérale, 37 il est permis de dire que ce modèle ressemble à l’espagnol et au suisse, en ce qu’elle est soumise à une même cour suprême, qui, connaît également du droit privé: le « Superior Tribunal de Justiça » (STJ Cour Suprême de Justice).38 En ce qui concerne la justice électorale, à l’inverse, le modèle est rigoureusement identique aux modèles allemand et portugais, avec une juridiction 27 ZILLER, Jacques. Administrations comparées. Les systèmes politico-administratifs de l’Europe des Douze. Paris: Montchrestien, 1993. p. 441. 28 FROMONT, op. cit. 29 ZILLER, op. cit. 30 Constitución Nacional (Sancionada por el congreso general constituyente el 1° de mayo de 1853, reformada y concordada por la convención nacional ad hoc el 25 de septiembre de 1860 y con las reformas de las convenciones de 1866, 1898, 1957 y 1994), art. 116. 31 Código Orgánico de Tribunales (Ley nº 7.421, de 15 de junio de 1943), art. 5º, 2. 32 Constitución Política de la República de Costa Rica de 1949 (Actualizada hasta Ley n° 8.365, del 15 de julio del 2003), arts. 152 e 153; Ley Orgánica del Poder Judicial (Ley nº 7.333/1993, modificada por la Ley nº 7.728, de 15 de diciembre de 1997). 33 Constitución Política del Perú de 1993, art. 139. 34 Constitución de la República Bolivariana de Venezuela de 1999, art. 259. 35 PERLINGEIRO; BLANKE; SOMMERMANN, op. cit., p. 65. 36 Regimento Interno do Superior Tribunal de Justiça (Règlement Interne du Tribunal Supérieur de Justice), art. 9, § 1º; Regimento Interno do Tribunal Regional Federal da 2ª Região (Règlement Interne du Tribunal Régional Fédéral de la 2ª Région), art. 2º, III, § 4º, et art. 13, III; Código de Organização e Divisão Judiciárias do Estado do Rio de Janeiro (Code de l’Organisation et de la Division Judiciaires de l’État de Rio de Janeiro), arts. 94, III, et 97. 37 Constitution de la République Fédérale du Brésil, du 5 octobre 1988, art. 109. 38 Ibid., art. 105. 162 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. administrative autonome et, au sommet, une cour suprême spécifique: le Tribunal Supérieur Electoral (TSE).39 4 PORTÉE DE LA JURIDICTION ADMINISTRATIVE En ce qui concerne la portée de la justice administrative, dans un premier lieu, nous devons nous interroger à propos du rôle primordial de ses principes et de ses normes spécifiques. Pour quelle raison le législateur devrait-il traiter de façon différente l’organisation des tribunaux responsables de rendre la justice administrative? Pour quelle raison le législateur devrait-il disposer de façon spécifique en ce qui concerne la procédure juridictionnelle relative aux causes soumises à la justice administrative? En effet, l’institution d’organes juridictionnels spécialisés compatibles avec une conception de justice de qualité et la consécration de principes et de règles spécifiques de justice administrative, qui considèrent, d’un côté, la fragilité du citoyen par rapport à l’Administration et, de l’autre, la pondération entre l’intérêt public et l’intérêt privé, sont des mesures dont l’objectif est d’assurer –en même temps- une protection juridictionnelle effective des droits du citoyen et du contrôle de la légalité de l’Administration Publique. De ce fait, quelles sont, exactement, les exigences qui justifient l’existence d’une justice administrative? En général, en ce qui concerne la définition de la compétence de la juridiction administrative, les systèmes d’Europe et d’Amérique Latine, appliquent les critères suivants: (1) celui des causes de droit administratif, où les conflits peuvent impliquer des autorités administratives ou des entités privées dans l’exercice de fonctions publiques, ainsi qu’il en est question en France,40 en Espagne,41 au Portugal,42 en Grèce,43 au Costa Rica,44 au Pérou, au Venezuela,45 en Colombie46 et en Argentine;47 (2) celui des causes relatives aux actes ou actions administratives, excluant la responsabilité civile ou les contrats administratifs, comme 39 Ibid., art. 118. 40 Code de Justice Administrative, art. L. 211-1. 41 Ley nº 23, de 7 de julio de 1998, art. 1º, 1. 42 Estatuto dos Tribunais Administrativos e Fiscais (Statut juridique des Tribunaux Administratifs et Fiscaux), (Loi nº 13, du 31 janvier 2002), art. 4º. 43 Σύνταγμα της Ελλάδας (Constitution du 9 juin 1975), arts. 94 et 95; Πράξη 1406/1983 (Loi nº 1.406, de 1983). 44 Código Procesal Contencioso-Administrativo (Ley nº 8.508, de 1º de enero de 2008), art. 1º. 45 Constitución de la República Bolivariana de Venezuela de 1999, art. 259. 46 Ley nº 1.437, de 18 de enero de 2011, art. 2º. 47 Ley Contencioso Administrativo de la Provincia de Buenos Aires (Ley nº 12.008, de 1º de junio de 1999), art. 1º. 163 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. en Allemagne,48 en Autriche49 et en Suisse;50 (3) celui des causes circonscrites aux intérêts légitimes, sauf en ce qui concerne les droits subjectifs, comme en Italie51 et en Belgique;52 (4) celui des causes de droit public ou privé, dans la mesure où c’est dans l’intérêt de l’Administration, ceci étant typique des systèmes de juridiction moniste, comme en Angleterre, en Irlande, en Norvège, au Danemark,53 au Chili54 et au Mexique.55 Sur ce point également, le système brésilien apparaît hybride. En général, en cohérence avec son système moniste de juridiction, prévaut le critère de l’intérêt de l’Administration, indépendamment de la nature publique ou privée de la cause, à l’exemple de la compétence des Chambres des Finances Publiques et de la Justice Fédérale, et de l’application de normes procédurales spécifiques, comme c’est le cas du régime spécial pour l’exécution des jugements obtenus en défaveur de l’Administration (precatório judicial),56 ou de l’existence de délais allongés pour la défense de l’Administration. 57 Cependant on trouve, enraciné dans le droit brésilien, lorsqu’il est question de la procédure juridictionnelle de référé “mandado de segurança”,58 une situation analogue à celle du système allemand, où l’intéressé peut contester les actes administratifs, même s’ils émanent d’entités privées exerçant un pouvoir public, sans pour autant pouvoir prétendre, devant le même juge, à une quelconque indemnisation. Par ailleurs, le “mandado de segurança” brésilien mériterait un chapitre à part, considérant son évidente crise d’identité: premièrement, parce qu’il est inspiré des writs, aujourd’hui substitués par la claim for judicial review;59 deuxièmement, de par ses racines dans l’amparo mexicain (juicio de amparo), qui est clairement une procédure de juridiction constitutionnelle; troisièmement, à cause de ses évidentes caractéristiques du recours en excès de pouvoir français, de l’époque à laquelle cette 48 Verwaltungsgerichtsordnung/VwGO (Código de Jurisdição Administrativa – Loi du 21 janvier 1960), § 40. 49 FROMONT, op. cit., p. 147. 50 Bundesgerichtsgesetz, BGG (Loi du 17 juin 2005); Bundesgesetz über das Verwaltungsverfahren (Loi du 20 décembre 1968), art. 5º. 51 Costituzione della Repubblica Italiana, de 27 de diciembre de 1947, art. 103. 52 FROMONT, op. cit., p. 150. 53 Ibid., p. 152-156. 54 Código Orgánico de Tribunales (Ley nº 7.421, de 15 de junio de 1943), art. 48. 55 Ley Orgánica del Tribunal Federal de Justicia Fiscal y Administrativa (dernière réforme publiée le 3 juin 2011), art. 14. 56 C’est-à dire injonction de payer obtenue en justice contre l'administration (ndt). 57 Constitution de la République Fédérale du Brésil, du 5 octobre 1988, arts. 100 et 109; Código de Processo Civil (Code de Procédure Civile), (Loi no 5.869, du 11 janvier 1973), arts. 191 e 730. 58 Loi nº 12.016, du 7 août 2009. (Procédure judiciaire spécifique permettant de contester des actes de l’Administration, ndt). 59 FROMONT, op. cit., p. 191. 164 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. mesure se limitait à l’annulation de l’acte administratif;60 finalement, parce qu’il se trouve actuellement inséré dans un système processuel et constitutionnel, au sein duquel, indépendamment de la procédure juridictionnelle choisie, l’intéressé peut formuler toute prétention à l’encontre l’Administration. 5 JUGES RENDANT LA JUSTICE ADMINISTRATIVE Des prérogatives d’indépendance personnelle et institutionnelle doivent être assurées à la fois aux agents publics et à la structure juridictionnelle ayant pour mission de protéger les droits et les intérêts relevant de la juridiction administrative. Ainsi, les juges doivent être inamovibles et nommés à vie, et leur rémunération doit être juste et adéquate. La sélection, la carrière et la discipline des juges doivent être confiées à un organisme qui garantisse son indépendance, afin d’éviter une structure juridictionnelle verticale, marquée par le carriérisme et la subordination hiérarchique entre les juges.61 En outre, l’entrée dans la carrière de juge – quel que soit le degré de juridiction – ne doit avoir lieu que par le biais d’un procédé ouvert, objectif et transparent, basé sur la qualification technique et la capacité professionnelle de l’intéressé. Ces principes, contenus dans le Code Modèle de Procédures Administratives – juridictionnelles et non contentieuses – pour l’Ibéro-Amérique,62 sont partiellement concrétisés par la Constitution brésilienne. En ce qui concerne le droit brésilien, la nomination comme juge du premier degré est rendue possible à tout citoyen se soumettant à un concours public sur épreuves et sur titres. Les juges du premier degré parviennent au second degré par le biais d’une promotion, selon le critère du mérite ou de l’ancienneté alternativement, il est, en outre, exigé d’eux un perfectionnement constant auprès des écoles de Magistrature. Certains postes disponibles au second degré sont attribués selon un critère politique, suivant les propositions effectuées par des ordres professionnels (Ordre des Avocats du Brésil – OAB et Ministère Public), puis par les tribunaux, la nomination finale dépendant du chef de l’Exécutif. En ce qui concerne la Cour Suprême de Justice « Superior Tribunal de Justiça » le critère est similaire, bien 60 Ibid., p. 164-168. 61 ZAFFARONI, Eugenio Raúl. Poder Judiciário. São Paulo: Revista dos Tribunais, 1995. 62 Código Modelo de Processos Administrativos – Judicial e Extrajudicial – para Ibero-América, arts. 26, 27, 28 et 29 (INSTITUT IBÉRO-AMERICAIN DE DROIT PROCESSUEL. Código Modelo de Processos Administrativos – Judicial e Extrajudicial – para Ibero-América. Buenos Aires: IIDP, 2012). 165 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. qu’existe en outre la garantie de l’intervention du Parlement.63 Au Brésil, l’exercice de la juridiction administrative par un juge non professionnel n’est pas prévue, sauf en ce qui concerne les « juizados especiais »64 mais bien que cette modalité bénéficie d’une autorisation constitutionnelle à l’art. 98, I et § 1º, elle n’a pas encore été transposée par une loi d’application. La Constitution de 1988, à l’art. 96 II, a doté les Tribunaux d’un pouvoir d’auto- organisation consistant en l’élection de leurs organes directifs, en l’élaboration de leurs règlements internes, en l’organisation de leurs secrétariats, des services auxiliaires et en la nomination des juges qui leur sont rattachés, qu’il s’agisse de pourvoir des postes de magistrats de carrière de cette juridiction en question, ou de pourvoir des postes nécessaires à l’administration de la Justice. L’autonomie administrative et financière se matérialise, de même, par la concession aux tribunaux du pouvoir d’élaborer leurs propositions budgétaires dans les limites établies avec les autres Pouvoirs, conformément à la Loi des Directives Budgétaires. Afin d’écarter la possibilité de dépendance externe, la Constitution à l’art. 95, établit, vis-à-vis des juges, des interdictions et des prérogatives,65 telles que: la nomination à vie, garantissant au juge la permanence dans ses fonctions jusqu’à l’âge de 70 ans, sauf en cas de condamnation définitive; l’inamovibilité, qui empêche que le juge puisse être transféré vers une autre juridiction, ce qui ne pourrait survenir que pour des motifs d’intérêt public et par décision du Tribunal à la majorité ou du Conseil National de Justice; et, finalement, l’irréductibilité de son salaire. Cependant, l’effectivité de ces prérogatives institutionnelles et personnelles de la magistrature est remise en cause, comme, par exemple, en fonction de la nature du processus de constitution du budget, il est permis que le Pouvoir Exécutif puisse exercer une influence sur la concession de ressources au Judiciaire, permettant que le caractère irréductible de la rémunération soit à peine nominal, sans que le maintien de la valeur réelle ne soit assuré. D’un point de vue interne, malgré le fait que les juges se sentent pleinement indépendants, la 63 Constitution de la République fédérale du Brésil, du 5 octobre 1988, art. 104. 64 Juridiction des petites causes équivalent partiel des tribunaux d’instance (ndt). 65 Aux juges sont appliquées les interdictions suivantes: I – exercer, même en régime de disponibilité, à un autre poste ou fonction, n’étant celle de magistrat; II – la perception, à n’importe quel titre et sous aucun prétexte, de frais de justice ou de participation au procès, tout comme la réception d’aides ou de contributions de personnes physiques, entités publiques ou privées; III – la participation à des activités politiques ou reliées à des partis politiques ; IV – l’exercice de la fonction d’avocat au cours du jugement ou dans le tribunal duquel il s’est démis, avant que se soient écoulés trois ans de la démission du poste pour exonération ou retraite. 166 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. solution selon laquelle les juges de 2º degré puissent détenir un pouvoir disciplinaire et de sélection des juges du 1º degré n’est pas idéale.66 Aux yeux de la société, cela peut donner l’impression d’une structure hiérarchique et carriériste, mettant en cause l’indépendance et l’impartialité, comme lorsque, par exemple, un juge de 1º degré se prononçant à propos de la légalité des actes administratifs de la Cour (2º degré) à laquelle il est rattaché ou encore des litiges intéressant ses membres. 6 LA NÉCESSITÉ DE REPRÉSENTATION PAR AVOCAT DEVANT LA JURIDICTION ADMINISTRATIVE La présence de l’avocat, devant la justice administrative, doit être considérée comme un devoir, et non comme un droit, y compris en ce qui concerne l’Administration, qui a besoin de se faire représenter par un professionnel du Droit. Le caractère obligatoire de la présence d’un avocat devant la juridiction administrative est justifié par la complexité des litiges de droit public. De cette façon, s’agissant d’un devoir, l’État devra concéder le bénéfice de l’assistance juridique gratuite à ceux qui n’ont pas les moyens d’y subvenir.67 Au Brésil, malgré le fait que la présence de l’avocat ne soit facultative que devant les « Juizados Especiais », en réalité, l’intéressé a toujours à sa portée un conseiller juridique, même s’il s’agit d’un fonctionnaire du Judiciaire, et le système de gratuité de justice (avocat et frais) fonctionne de façon assez efficace et étendue au sein de la juridiction administrative.68 7 LES PRÉTENTIONS RECEVABLES ET L’ÉTENDUE DU CONTRÔLE JURIDICTIONNEL S’agissant de son étendue, la compétence de la juridiction administrative doit être pleine, car elle doit être capable de réaliser intégralement le droit subjectif allégué et, doit donc, correspondre, si besoin, à une déclaration, annulation, injonct ion de faire, de ne pas faire, de donner ou de payer, y compris par le biais de mesures d’urgence ou d’exécution 66 ZAFFARONI, , Eugenio Raúl. Poder Judiciário. São Paulo: Revista dos Tribunais, 1995. 67 INSTITUT IBERO-AMÉRICAIN DE DROIT PROCESSUEL. Código Modelo de Processos Administrativos – Judicial e Extrajudicial – para Ibero-América, op. cit., arts. 32, 33 e 34. 68 Constitution de la République Fédérale du Brésil, du 5 octobre 1988, art. 5º, LXXIV; Loi nº 1.060, du 5 février 1950. 167 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. forcée.69 De cette plénitude de juridiction dépendent une protection juridictionnelle effective et l’État de Droit, dépassant ainsi le dogme selon lequel le juge ne peut imposer à l’Administration des obligations de faire, ni lui appliquer des amendes punitives ou coercitives (contempt of court civil et criminal), ni même exproprier ou mettre en gage des biens publics non essentiels.70 Le caractère effectif de la juridiction administrative n’est limité que par l’intérêt public, s’il est ponctuellement allégué et démontré, en observant les garanties d’une procédure légale, par le biais de mesures compensatoires en faveur de l’intéressé. Le droit brésilien a beaucoup évolué à ce niveau-là. Le Code de Procédure Civile, applicable subsidiairement à la juridiction administrative, admet que toute sorte de prétention soit portée en justice à l’encontre de l’Administration. Des mesures d’urgence et d’exécution forcée sont prévues et il y a même la possibilité, en cas de stricte nécessité, d’obtenir le paiement d’une somme en espèces, conformément à la jurisprudence de la Cour Suprême Fédérale.71 Cependant, la difficulté majeure repose sur la pratique de l’Administration de remettre en cause les mesures d’exécution forcée sur la simple allégation d’atteinte à l’intérêt public, par le procédé de “suspension de mesure provisoire” ou de “suspension de l’exécution du jugement”, ce qui ne s’encadre pas exactement avec le principe du contradictoire.72 L’exclusion de certains actes publics du contrôle juridictionnel continue à se vérifier dans la culture de certains systèmes, même si, sur le plan dogmatique, ne puisse plus être soutenue l’existence d’une catégorie spéciale d’actes qui, ontologiquement ne diffèrent d’ailleurs en rien des autres actes émis par l’Administration. 73 Il est indéniable que l’impossibilité de soumettre au contrôle juridictionnel le contenu politique d’actes publics n’est qu’un mythe. Cette question mérite d’être revisitée en partant des principes fondamentaux de juridiction administrative, en parallèle avec ceux de la juridiction constitutionnelle. Au Brésil, le juge “bouche de la loi” est, en fait, une figure de rhétorique.74 La réitération de la judiciarisation des politiques publiques de santé, affirmée par les différentes 69 INSTITUT IBÉRO-AMÉRICAIN DE DROIT PROCESSUEL. Código Modelo de Processos Administrativos – Judicial e Extrajudicial – para Ibero-América, op. cit., Exposition de Motifs. 70 Ibid., Exposition de Motifs. 71 BRÉSIL. Cour Suprême Fédérale. AI 59.7182. 2ª Classe, Rapporteur min. Cezar Peluzo, DJ 6.11.2006. 72 Loi nº 8.437, du 30 juin 1992, art. 4º. 73 WOLFF, Hans J.; BACHOF, Otto; STOBER, Rolf. Direito administrativo.Traduction Antônio F. de Sousa. Lisbonne: Fondation Calouste Gulbenkian, 2006. p. 247; GARCÍA DE ENTERRÍA, Eduardo. La lucha contra las inmunidades del poder. 3. ed. Madri: Civitas, 1995. p. 70-78). 74 SADEK, Maria Teresa. Judiciário e arena pública: um olhar a partir da ciência política. In: GRINOVER, Ada Pellegrini; WATANABE, Kazuo (Orgs.). O controle jurisdicional de políticas públicas. 1. ed. Rio de Janeiro: Forense, 2011. p. 1-33. 168 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. sphères du Judiciaire brésilien, aux niveaux constitutionnel ou administratif, est un parfait exemple du fait qu’aucun acte émis par le pouvoir public ne peut être considéré à l'abri de la Justice.75 Le contrôle juridictionnel des activités administratives doit englober, non seulement la forme et de contenu de l’acte administratif, mais aussi son caractère discrétionnaire s’il dépasse les limites autorisées par la loi, s’il dévie de sa finalité ou s’il porte atteinte aux droits ou principes fondamentaux, comme ceux de l’égalité, de la sécurité juridique, de la confiance légitime, de la proportionnalité et du raisonnable.76 Dans ce contexte, il est attendu de l’Administration un comportement au premier chef éthique et conforme à l’État de Droit, ayant comme principal objectif le respect des droits fondamentaux, et qu’elle agisse en obéissant aux principes du droit administratif, parmi lesquels je souligne les suivants. 8 PRINCIPE DE LÉGALITÉ Le principe de légalité vise la soumission de l’Administration au droit, et le fait d’être prévu par les lois de procédure administrative tend à le renforcer, ainsi qu’il en est question dans la loi péruvienne de procédures administratives: “Las autoridades administrativas deben actuar con respeto a la Constitución, la ley y al derecho, dentro de las facultades que le estén atribuidas y de acuerdo con los fines para los que les fueron conferidas.”77 En outre, il convient de relever que l’Administration doit veiller non seulement à la légalité ou à la constitutionnalité, mais aussi à la conventionnalité, et est ainsi autorisée à ne pas exécuter une loi ou une norme administrative à laquelle elle est soumise si elle la considère anticonventionnelle ou anticonstitutionnelle, tant que, sans préjudice du principe de subordination hiérarchique, elle en réfère aux organes de contrôle compétents afin que ceux- ci en déclarent l’anticonventionnalité ou l’inconstitutionnalité. 78 Cependant, entre nous, en 75 BRÉSIL. Cour Suprême Fédérale, Plenum. SL 47 AgR. Rapporteur min. Gilmar Mendes, j. 17.3.2010, DJ 30.4.2010. 76 INSTITUT IBÉRO-AMÉRICAIN DE DROIT PROCESSUEL. Código Modelo de Processos Administrativos – Judicial e Extrajudicial – para Ibero-América, op. cit., art., art. 25. 77 PÉROU. Ley del Procedimiento Administrativo General (Lei nº 27.444, de 10 de abril de 2001), art. IV, 1.1. 78 Henrique Savonitti Miranda met l’accent sur la controverse doctrinale au Brésil à propos de la possibilité que l’Administration refuse, simplement, d’exécuter des lois ou actes normatifs anticonstitutionnels. À faveur: Carlos Maximiliano; Francisco Campos; José Celso de Mello Filho; Caio Tácito; Manoel Gonçalves Ferreira Filho; Miguel Reale; Hely Lopes Meirelles. Contre: Celso Antônio Bandeira de Mello; Gilmar Ferreira Mendes; 169 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. dépit de l’absence de prévision législative ou constitutionnelle expresse, s’impose à l’Administration l’initiative de rendre opérationnel de façon efficace ce procédé de rapport aux organes compétents, tant n’est pas justifiable son omission ou sa soumissio n, dans l’attente d’une intervention juridictionnelle, nationale ou internationale, à la loi anticonstitutionnelle ou anticonventionnelle. À propos de l’absence d’une loi nationale relative au contrôle de la conventionalité, la Cour Interaméricaine des Droits Humains a décidé, litteris: En relación con las prácticas judiciales, este Tribunal ha establecido en su jurisprudencia que es consciente de que los jueces y tribunales internos están sujetos al imperio de la ley y, por ello, están obligados a aplicar las disposiciones vigentes en el ordenamiento jurídico. Pero cuando un Estado ha ratificado un tratado internacional como la Convención Americana, sus jueces, como parte del aparato del Estado, también están sometidos a ella, lo que les obliga a velar porque los efectos de las disposiciones de la Convención no se vean mermados por la aplicación de leyes contrarias a su objeto y fin, que desde un inicio carecen de efectos jurídicos. En otras palabras, el Poder Judicial debe ejercer un “control de convencionalidad” ex officio entre las normas internas y la Convención Americana, evidentemente en el marco de sus respectivas competencias y de las regulaciones procesales correspondientes. En esta tarea, el Poder Judicial debe tener en cuenta no solamente el tratado, sino también la interpretación que del mismo ha hecho la Corte Interamericana, intérprete última de la Convención Americana. De tal manera, es necesario que las interpretaciones constitucionales y legislativas referidas a los criterios de competencia material y personal de la jurisdicción militar en México, se adecuen a los principios establecidos en la jurisprudencia de este Tribunal, los cuales han sido reiterados en el presente caso. Bajo ese entendido, este Tribunal considera que no es necesario ordenar la modificación del contenido normativo que regula el artículo 13 de la Constitución Política de los Estados Unidos Mexicanos. 79 8 PRINCIPES DE PROPORTIONNALITÉ ET PRINCIPE DU RAISONNABLE La doctrine brésilienne tend à établir une identité entre les principes du raisonnable et de proportionnalité. Selon Bandeira de Mello, Zeno Veloso (MIRANDA, Henrique Savonitti. Licitações e contratos administrativos.Brasília: École Nationale de l’Administration Publique, 2004). Je pense, néanmoins, qu’il n’y a pas controverse concernant la possibilité de rapport quant à l’anti constitutionnalité auprès de l’organe compétent afin qu’il en soit fait état devant la Cour Suprême Fédérale. 79 CORTE INTERAMERICANA DE DIREITOS HUMANOS. Caso Radilla Pacheco vs. México. Excepciones Preliminares, Fondo, Reparaciones y Costas. Sentencia de 23 de noviembre de 2009. Serie C No. 209. 170 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. à proprement parler, le principe de proportionnalité n'est qu'une facette du principe du raisonnable. Il mérite une attention particulière, une référence spéciale, de façon à ce que l'on puisse mieux distinguer la physionomie d'un vice spécifique qui peut surgir et se montrer sous l'aspect d'un acte disproportionné, en soulignant, par conséquent, les possibilités de correction juridictionnelle ancrées dans ce fondement. Étant un aspect spécifique du principe du raisonnable, il est entendu que leur matrices constitutionnelles sont identiques. 80 Bien que ces deux principes soient mentionnés à l'art. 2 de la loi n° 9.784/98, seul celui de la proportionnalité y est explicité dans les termes suivants: «adéquation entre moyens et fins, est interdite l'imposition d'obligations, de restrictions et de sanctions supérieures en proportion à celles qui sont strictement nécessaires à l'observance de l'intérêt public » (art. 2, VI). Il convient de noter que, dans la législation, le principe ci-dessus, est lié à l'«intérêt public» et sera naturellement utilisé parallèlement aux principes d'égalité, de bonne foi et de protection de la confiance légitime, lors de l'exercice d'un pouvoir administratif discrétionnaire. 9 PRINCIPE D’ÉGALITÉ Le pouvoir judiciaire doit être le destinataire du principe d'égalité, cherchant à traiter de la même façon les citoyens se trouvant dans la même situation de fait. A partir de cette idée est justifiée l’adoption de certains instruments procéduraux tels que: les actions collectives, les « súmulas vinculantes »81 et le procès exemplaire, servant également l'idée d'un large accès à la justice et de la limitation des procédures juridictionnelles répétitives ou des causes de masse. Toutefois, s’agissant des causes de droit public, où est en jeu un comportement ou une action administrative de portée générale, l'égalité découlant de la prestation juridictionnelle est doublement nécessaire, principalement en raison du devoir d'égalité depuis toujours inhérent à l'administration publique, dans les sphères aussi bien matérielle qu’extrajuridictionnelle.82 80 MELLO, Celso Antônio Bandeira de. Curso de direito administrativo.21. ed. São Paulo: Malheiros, 2006. p. 107-108. 81 Arrêt de principe du STF à caractère contraignant (ndt). 82 PERLINGEIRO, Ricardo. O princípio da isonomia na tutela judicial individual e coletiva, e em outros meios de solução de conflitos, junto ao SUS e aos planos privados de saúde. Dans: Noble, Milton; JOURS, Ricardo (s Org.). O Conselho Nacional de Justiça e os desafios da efetivação do direito à saúde. Belo Horizonte: Forum, 2011. p. 429-441 171 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. Il ne serait pas logique qu'une action administrative originellement destinée à la communauté, une fois judiciarisée, ne soit opposable qu’à ceux étant disposés à l’introduire ; le pouvoir judiciaire ne pouvant être associé à une exégèse capable de rompre avec le principe d'égalité administrative. D'autre part, le principe d''égalité devant être observé par l'administration ne peut pas servir de justification à la négation de droits subjectifs. En effet, concéder à un citoyen un droit qui pourrait également être étendu à tous ceux se trouvant dans la même situation, mais sans l’étendre effectivement, fait imploser l'idée d'égalité. L'erreur, cependant, réside dans le fait que l'Administration n'étende pas ce bénéfice, et non dans le fait que le pouvoir Judiciaire ne reconnaisse pas ce droit.83 En effet, l'un des plus grands défis du droit administratif contemporain, est le manque d'uniformité des décisions administratives concernant les intéressés dans la même situation de fait, alimentant ainsi une pluralité de demandes répétitives, en particulier au niveau de la sphère juridictionnelle, mettant ainsi potentiellement en jeu la sécurité juridique. En Europe, dans certains systèmes nationaux, le principe d'égalité a du mal à être appliqué aux décisions administratives et la doctrine s’est peu dédiée aux recherches sur ce sujet.84 Selon le Code Modèle de Procédures Administratives pour l'Ibéro-Amérique, l'égalité de l'Administration doit être de telle sorte que, lorsque La question de fond d’une prétention individuelle est rattachée aux effets juridiques d’un comportement administratif de portée générale, la solution du conflit doit devenir de l’intérêt de la collectivité destinataire de ce comportement et il en résulte que la solution ne saurait être trouvée qu’en une décision administrative unique, valant erga omnes. 85 En conséquence directe, les accords judiciaires concernant des normes administratives ou des actions d'intérêt général administratif, atteindraient nécessairement tous ceux qui se trouveraient dans la même situation de fait, même s'ils n'ont pas participé à ces accords.86 83 BRÉSIL. Tribunal Régional Fédéral de la 2ª Region. AG 201102010109190. 5a Classe. Rapporteur juge Ricardo Perlingeiro, E-DJF2R 13.2.2012. 84 “L’existence du principe d’égalité dans le droit administratif ne fait l’objet d’aucune hésitation dans les divers pays étudiés. Certes le droit britannique a longtemps préféré parler de rationalité et de cohérence plutôt que d’égalité, même si les solutions concrètes étaient pratiquement les mêmes; mais depuis une vingtaine d’années, le principe d’égalité est ouvertement appliqué par le juge britannique.” FROMONT, op. cit., p. 253-256. 85 INSTITUT IBÉRO-AMÉRICAIN de DROIT PROCESSUEL. Código Modelo de Processos Administrativos – Judicial e Extrajudicial – para Ibero-América, op. cit., art. 5º. 86 Ibid., art. 72, II. 172 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. 10 PRINCIPES DE SÉCURITÉ JURIDIQUE ET DE CONFIANCE LÉGITIME La sécurité juridique doit opérer de façon à limiter le pouvoir d’autocensure de ses propres actes par l'administration. L'annulation des actes, des normes ou des décisions administratives entachés d'illégalité, mais ayant apporté des bénéfices aux citoyens, dépend d'une procédure juridictionnelle préalable et doit survenir, d’un point de vue objectif, dans un délai déterminé, sauf s'il y a preuve de mauvaise foi, ou, selon un point de vue subjectif, lorsque n'est pas remise en cause la confiance de l'intéressé en la stabilité du comportement de l'Administration.87 Le principe de la confiance légitime, arrimé à une dimension subjective de la notion de bonne foi basée sur les droits fondamentaux, dérive des principes de la sécurité juridique et de l'État de Droit, il oriente la loi allemande, selon laquelle un acte administratif invalide qui octroie ou est la condition d’une prestation pécuniaire immédiate ou échelonnée dans le temps, ne peut être invalidé si le bénéficiaire a cru dans la stabilité de l’acte administratif et si, sous réserve de l’intérêt public à le voir invalidé, cette confiance est digne de protection ; en règle générale on estime que la confiance est digne de protection si le bénéficiaire a disposé des prestations octroyées ou s’il a déjà conclu un contrat visant à en disposer, contrat qu’il ne peut plus annuler ou l’annulant à des conditions par trop préjudiciables pour lui. 88 En dehors de ces cas, une fois abrogé l'acte invalide et pesé l'intérêt public, il faut déterminer la réparation à octroyer sur la base de la confiance en sa stabilité.89 Dans ces deux cas, la notion de confiance est écartée en présence de : dol, menace, corruption, connaissance de l'invalidité ou méconnaissance de celle-ci pour cause de faute grave de l'intéressé, obtention de l'acte à partir de données inexactes ou incomplètes.90 Parallèlement, la validation putative, passé le délai d’un an à partir de la date de la prise de connaissance de l'invalidité, ne connaît d’exceptions qu’en cas de fraude, de menace et de corruption, étant ainsi écartés les autres aspects de la notion de confiance.91 Pour Forsthoff, dans le droit allemand, il n'existe que deux situations pour l'annulation des actes administratifs: abrogation (invalidation de l'acte n’ayant eu d’effet que 87 Ibid., arts. 19 e 20. 88 Verwaltungsverfahrensgesetz/VwVfG (Code Allemand de Procédures Administratives, du 25 mai 1976), § 48, numéro 2. 89 Ibid., § 48, numéro 3. 90 Ibid., § 48, numéro 2, points 1, 2 et 3; numéro 3, deuxième phrase. 91 Ibid., § 48, numéro 4. 173 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. sur le plan financier) et la révocation (invalidité d'un acte produisant des effets favorables). En principe, il n'est pas lieu à «libre» révocation, sauf si l'acte invalide est également antijuridique, comme dans les cas de dol ou lorsqu’il y a de nouvelles circonstances de fait et de droit.92 En droit administratif français, le principe de sécurité juridique est associé aux principes de non-rétroactivité et de respect des droits acquis (situations consolidées légalement). S'il y a modification d'une situation stabilisée, bien qu’illégale, l'Administration française concilie les principes de sécurité juridique avec l'“obligation de rétablir une situation conforme au droit” et, de ce fait, la décision administrative constitutive de «droits» contra legem peut être annulée, mais dans un certain délai.93 C'est la logique objective du droit français. En droit britannique, la sécurité juridique est liée à la protection de la confiance légitime (legitimate expectations), de sorte que l'Administration ne doive pas induire l'intéressé en erreur, mais en ce qui concerne les situations consolidées illégalement, le droit anglais en arrive à être plus sévère que le droit français, en n’admettant jamais la possibilité de droits subjectifs contra legem.94 Toutefois, le droit administratif européen, qui exerce une influence croissante sur les systèmes nationaux européens, met l'accent sur le principe de la confiance légitime d'origine allemande.95 Partiellement en contradiction avec les termes de la súmula vinculante96 numéro 473 de la Cour Suprême Fédérale («L’Administration peut annuler ses propres actes lors qu'ils sont entachés de vices qui les rendent illégaux, car ils ne créent aucun droit...») la loi n°9.784/99 a incorporé au droit brésilien le principe objectif français de sécurité juridique, parallèlement au subjectivisme allemand et à celui de confiance légitime, en particulier sur deux points: (1) déchéance du pouvoir d'annuler les actes administratifs ayant des effets favorables, au bout de cinq ans, sauf si la mauvaise foi est établie, (2) possibilité de validation putative des actes dont les défauts ne portent pas préjudice à l'intérêt public ou aux tiers. L'absence de mauvaise foi - équivalant à l'absence de dol- associée à l’échéance du délai, justifient la validation d’actes ayant des effets favorables, bien que contraires à la loi et 92 FORSTHOFF, Ernst. Tratado de derecho administrativo. Traduction Legaz Lacambra, Garrido Falla et Gómez de Ortega y Junge. Madrid: Instituto de Estudios Politicos, 1958. p. 359 et 363. 93 FROMONT, Michel. Droit administratif des Etats européens. Paris: PUF, 2006. p. 261-269. 94 Ibid., p. 268. 95 SIRINELLI, Jean. Les transformations du droit administratif par le droit de l’Union Européenne. Paris: LGDJ, 2011. p. 499. 96 Précédent jurisprudentiel s’imposant aux juges (ndt). 174 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. catalogués comme annulables (art. 54 de la Loi n ° 9.784/99: “L’Administration est déchue de son droit d'annuler les actes administratifs produisant des effets favorables au regard de ses destinataires à compter de cinq ans à partir de la date à laquelle ils ont été pratiqués, sauf si la mauvaise foi est établie”). La règle est analogue à celle que l'on trouve dans la VwVfG, § 48, numéro 4. Selon les dispositions de l'art. 55 de la loi n° 9.784/99 («Les actes présentant des défauts réparables, pourront être validés putativement par l’Administration elle-même, dans une décision établissant clairement qu’ils ne portent atteinte ni à l’intérêt public ni aux droits des tiers.»), la validation putative en tout temps d’actes illégaux dépend de l'absence d'atteinte à l'intérêt public, qui, soulignons-le, ne peut être confondu avec les intérêts de l'Administration. Cependant, malgré cette lacune, la validation putative doit être limitée, uniquement lorsqu’elle est nécessaire à satisfaire les intérêts de ceux qui en bénéficient, en raison de la confiance manifestée à l’égard des Pouvoirs Publics et démontrée à chaque fois qu'il y aura de sérieuses raisons de croire en la stabilité de l'acte administratif. Cette règle passe alors pour avoir un lien direct avec le principe de la confiance légitime suivant l’exemple du VwVfG, § 48, numéros 2 et 3. En ce qui concerne la protection des droits acquis comme condition à la révocation des actes administratifs, à l'art. 53 de la Loi n° 9.784/99, il semble clair que, dans des conditions normales, l'Administration ne révoque pas des actes licites constitutifs de droits légitimes. Par conséquent, la norme n'aurait de sens que si le terme "révocation" était appréhendé sous le point de vue allemand, quant à l'annulation des actes invalides ayant des effets favorables, et que les «droits acquis» dérivaient précisément de ces effets favorables. 97 L'article ci-dessus pourrait également être interprété, comme dans la jurisprudence française, à partir de l'existence de deux catégories de décisions administratives, celles constitutives de droits (par exemple, celles conférant un avantage pécuniaire) et celles qui ne créent pas de droits (telles que celles résultant d’un pouvoir de police). Cependant, en ce qui concerne cette dernière uniquement, des faits postérieurs impactant ces droits pourraient conduire à l'annulation de l'acte.98 Dans ce contexte, je pense qu'au Brésil, est admissible l'exégèse selon laquelle, tant qu'il n'y a pas atteinte à l'intérêt public, les effets favorables et consommés des actes invalides doivent être préservés, de même que la réparation des dommages causés, en raison de la 97 FORSTHOFF, op. cit., p. 359 e 363. 98 FROMONT, op. cit., p. 266. 175 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. confiance dont est dépositaire l'Administration. En l'absence de dol et passé un délai de cinq ans, en plus de préserver les effets consommés, l'acte administratif illégal est validé putativement. 11 PRINCIPES DU PROCÈS ÉQUITABLE (DROITS DE LA DÉFENSE ET CONTRADICTOIRE) La procédure administrative doit être préalable afin de rendre légitime l'élaboration - soulignons-le - de tous les actes administratifs individuels ayant des effets ponctuels et restrictifs de droits ou d'intérêts. Il est important de souligner que la possibilité d'un recours administratif contradictoire a posteriori, contestant l'acte administratif, n'exclut pas l'obligation d'une procédure préalable à la réalisation de ce même acte; la procédure administrative étant l'un des éléments constitutifs de l'acte administratif. À ce sujet, les principes du contradictoire et de l’exercice des droits de la défense inhérents à la procédure administrative doivent respecter non seulement le droit d'être entendu – d’avoir son day in court - ou de produire des preuves, mais surtout celui d'obtenir une décision publique motivée, basée sur les arguments de fait et de droit produits par les parties.99 C’est la tendance de la jurisprudence de la Cour Suprême Fédérale, qui sous l’influence de la jurisprudence du Bundesverfassungsgericht, considère que le droit à la défense et au contradictoire impliquent non seulement le droit de se manifester et d’être informé, mais également le droit de l’individu de voir ses arguments pris en compte par l’organe juridictionnel.100 Mais ce qui semble évident, constitue encore aujourd’hui un défi au regard des résistances de l’Administration Publique brésilienne. Prenons l'exemple de deux cas paradigmatiques que l'on retrouve fréquemment dans les tribunaux, l'un concernant les actes administratifs individuels, l'autre les actes relatifs administratifs généraux. 12.1 La retenue sur salaire des fonctionnaires publics 99 INSTITUT IBÉRO-AMERICAIN DE DROIT PROCESSUEL. Código Modelo de Processos Administrativos – Judicial e Extrajudicial – para Ibero-América, op. cit, Exposition de Motifs. 100 BRÉSIL. Cour Suprême Fédérale. MS 25.787-3/DF. Rapporteur min. Gilmar Mendes. Brasília, DF. 176 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. Le premier exemple concerne la retenue sur salaire des fonctionnaires publics, ayant pour but la restitution des sommes indûment versées, permise par la Loi n° 8.112/29101, sans qu’ils ne puissent pour autant bénéficier d'une procédure administrative préalable. L'idée selon laquelle l'Administration Publique détient, pour le recouvrement de dettes, le pouvoir de procéder à des retenues sur la rémunération de ses propres fonctionnaires, sans que ne soient observées les garanties d’un procès équitable, ainsi que des affirmations du type "le fonctionnaire public ne dispose d’aucun droit acquis à un régime statutaire"102, peuvent être associées aux vestiges d'une conception de la fin du XIXe siècle, les nommées «relations spéciales de pouvoir», selon lesquelles les fonctionnaires, pour satisfaire les prétentions découlant de leur lien de subordination à l’Etat, étaient toujours soumis à des statuts ou à des normes spéciales auxquelles ne pouvaient s’appliquer les droits fondamentaux, le principe de légalité ou de sécurité juridique.103 Ces relations spéciales de droit public, institutionnalisées constitutionnellement, se caractérisaient par un ordre disciplinaire statutaire propre, avec une force obligatoire uniquement interne104, fondées et limitées tant par l'application de la loi, comme, par exemple, dans les relations découlant du service militaire obligatoire, que par la volonté de l'intéressé lui-même, tel que dans les relations avec les fonctionnaires publics ou les militaires de carrière. À l'époque, on en venait à dire que l'enseignant pouvait, "sans détours, détenir et emprisonner l'étudiant négligent»,105 le citoyen quittait la société et entrait dans l'organisation institutionnelle de l'État.106 Cette vision, à l'époque liée à un État de Droit purement formel, est aujourd'hui dépassée. En Allemagne, la rupture définitive avec l'exégèse selon laquelle les relations spéciales de pouvoir créaient des espaces juridiquement vides a eu lieu à partir de la décision de la Cour Constitutionnelle Fédérale, qui, en date du 14 mars 1972, a affirmé que 101 Loi nº 8.112, du 11 novembre 1990 (Rédaction élaborée à partir de la Mesure Provisoire nº 2.225-45, du 4.9.2001), art. 46. 102 BRÉSIL. Cour Suprême Fédérale. AI 64.1911, AgR. 1ª Classe. Rapporteur min. Carmen Lúcia, j. 8.9.2009, DJe 1.10.2009; BRASIL. Cour Suprême Fédérale. RE 116.683. Rapporteur min. Celso de Mello, DJ 13.3.1993; BRÉSIL. Cour Suprême Fédérale. AI 685-866-AgR. Rapporteur min. Ricardo Lewandowski, DJe 22.5.2009. 103 MAURER, Hartmut. Direito administrativo geral. Barueri: Manole, 2006. p. 195. 104 MAYER, Otto. Derecho administrativo alemán. Buenos Aires: Depalma, 1982. t. I, § 10, III, p. 170-171. FORSTHOFF, op. cit., p. 201. 105 W. Jellinek, VerwR S. 122, S. 341, apud MAURER, op. cit., p. 195. 106 WOLFF; BACHOF; STOBER, Direito administrativo. Traduction Antônio F. de Sousa. Lisboa: Fundação Calouste Gulbenkian, 2006..p. 111. 177 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. les droits fondamentaux peuvent également être invoqués pour la mise en œuvre de sanctions administratives.107 Il est clair que les prétentions d'un fonctionnaire se rapportant exclusivement à ses attributions administratives, ne sont qu'apparentes et les conflits éventuels doivent être résolus interna corporis par l'Administration elle-même, n'existant pas, dans ces cas, un droit subjectif proprement dit. L’Administration n’a pas de droits à l’égard d’elle-même, tel était le sens de l’institut de la « relation spéciale de pouvoir », associé à un cadre interne, et partant, juridiquement vide. D’où, la juste affirmation selon laquelle le Pouvoir Judiciaire ne doit pas connaître des questions interna corporis de l'Administration; elle doit respecter les statuts, règles et règlements, qui, par exemple, établissent les critères de choix interne d'un dirigeant d'une université publique (autonomie universitaire) ou encore d'un tribunal, puisque les effets d'un conflit de cette nature s'épuisent internement et qu’il n’y a pas, en toute logique, de droits subjectifs à protéger juridictionnellement. Il en va de même en ce qui concerne la structure administrative du Pouvoir Législatif (élection à des commissions parlementaires, etc.). Toutefois, si un fonctionnaire allègue une atteinte à sa sphère patrimoniale, la prétention correspondante, même si elle provient directement de son lien à l'administration, devra être considérée sous couvert des droits fondamentaux. A la différence de ce qui s’est déjà dit par le passé, le fonctionnaire public n’est plus l’objet d’un « pouvoir spécial », mais il demeure un sujet de droit. 108 12.2 Les droits de la défense dans les décisions du TCU La deuxième situation concerne la procédure administrative préalable comme condition des décisions rendues par la Cour des Comptes. Pendant de nombreuses années, au Brésil a prévalu l'idée selon laquelle, au cours d'une procédure administrative devant la Cour des Comptes, la garantie du droit à la défense aux éventuels intéressés n'était pas nécessaire. Ceci car cette procédure s'entendait comme exclusivement retournée contre l'Administration, constituant, ainsi, une procédure interne de contrôle de la légalité de l'Administration. Le cas échéant, les intéressés devraient faire valoir directement leurs droits auprès de l'administration. Cependant, en réalité, 107 BverfGE, 33, 1. 108 WOLFF; BACHOF; STOBER, op. cit., p. 494. 178 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. l'Administration, orientée par le principe de la subordination hiérarchique, ne serait en aucun cas en mesure de contrarier la position prise par la Cour des Comptes, rendant ainsi le droit à la défense purement protocolaire, sans aucun effet pratique. En 2007, la Cour Suprême Fédérale a publié la « súmula vinculante » numéro 3, en ces termes: “Au cours des procédures portées devant la Cour des Comptes de l'Union, sont assurés le contradictoire et les droits de la défense lorsqu'il peut résulter de la décision l'annulation ou la révocation d'un acte administratif dont bénéficie l'intéressé [...]”.109 Toutefois, la Cour des Comptes, lors de l'interprétation de cet arrêt, a décidé que Il n'appartient pas au TCU d'instaurer une procédure contradictoire à tous ceux que concernent les décisions génériques du Tribunal - prises dans l'exercice de sa compétence constitutionnelle d'exiger des personnes soumises à sa juridiction la parfaite application de la loi - c’est-à-dire de contenu uniquement objectif, sans tenir compte des situations concrètes et subjectives, donc sans la présence du sujet passif déterminé. 110 Ainsi que nous l'avons mentionné plus haut, toute procédure administrative doit assurer le respect des droits de la défense et du principe du contradictoire, dans le but de légitimer la prise d’actes ayant une répercussion envers les intéressés. Cependant, de fait, en raison de l'essence même de la procédure administrative, seuls les actes et les décisions administratives individuels permettent l'exercice préalable du droit à la défense. Il faut reconnaître que, lorsque l'on parle de la constitution d'actes généraux, concrets ou abstraits, ou d'actes individuels quant à leurs effets généraux, la procédure administrative prévoit le mécanisme du contradictoire différé ou reporté. Dans ces cas-là, en raison de l'impossibilité de convoquer chaque individu impliqué afin de défendre ses intérêts, cette diligence est remplacée par une consultation publique ou une audience publique, prévues par la législation brésilienne aux arts. 31 et 32 de la Loi n° 9.784/1999, ce procédé comporte une correspondance dans les ordres juridiques d'autres pays d'Amérique Latine, comme le Costa Rica, le Pérou, le Mexique et le Venezuela.111 109 BRÉSIL. Cour Suprême Fédérale. Súmula Vinculante nº 3. Session Plenière, 30 mai 2007. Brésilia, DF, DJe nº 31 de 6.6.2007, p. 1. 110 BRASIL. Tribunal des Comptes de l’Union. Acórdão (Arrêt) 2.553/2009. Session Plénière. Rapporteur min. José Jorge, DJ 4.11.2009. 111 BREWER-CARÍAS, Allan. Principios del procedimiento administrativo en América Latina. Bogotá: Legis, 2003. p. 98-99. En France, la participation des intéressés au processus de prise de décisions d'intérêt collectif constitue un débat difficile, elle est prise en charge par la Commission Nationale de Débat Public, ayant aujourd'hui un statut d'autorité administrative indépendante et elle a la fonction d'assurer le renforcement de la participation populaire dans le processus d'élaboration de projets urbains ayant un impact économique et 179 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. En outre, il convient de souligner que sera ultérieurement garantie à l'intéressé la faculté d'amorcer une nouvelle procédure administrative disposant d’une totale possibilité de défense de façon à écarter les effets individuels de l'acte général provenant de la procédure administrative antérieure, au cours de laquelle il a été représenté par les entités qui ont pu participer aux audiences et aux consultations publiques. Rappelons, enfin, que les questions d'intérêt général ne peuvent être décidées par une autorité administrative de degré inférieur à celle qui a donné lieu au conflit. La compétence incombera à l'autorité qui détient le pouvoir d'autocensure s’agissant de la question de fond soulevée par les intéressés. Ainsi, dans le cas où la prétention implique la déclaration d'invalidité ou d'illégalité d'un acte administratif, seule l'autorité administrative compétente pour annuler un acte ou son supérieur pourra juger la procédure, sous peine d’irrespect ou d’insubordination administrative. Par conséquent, les Tribunaux des Comptes doivent toujours s'abstenir de déléguer à l'Administration la garantie des droits de la défense et du principe du contradictoire, et doivent commencer à recevoir, eux-mêmes, les procédures administratives visant à la contestation individuelle de leurs décisions où la question de fond est d'intérêt général, afin d'assurer le respect des garanties d'un procès équitable. Il convient en outre de souligner que les effets favorables de la solution finale sont nécessairement étendus à tous ceux se trouvant dans la même situation de fait.112 13 LA RÉALITÉ DE L’ADMINISTRATION BRÉSILIENNE Je considère que, d'une manière générale, la justice administrative brésilienne, sa structure organique, ses juges, ses normes et ses principes procéduraux, sont en accord avec les principes fondamentaux de la protection juridictionnelle effective et de l'État de droit. environnemental. (POCHARD, Marcel. La Administración Pública y la protección de los derechos fundamentales. In: CONSEJO DE ESTADO DE LA REPÚBLICA DE COLOMBIA. Seminario Franco- Colombiano sobre la Reforma a la Jurisdicción Contencioso Administrativa. Bogotá: Imprenta Nacional de Colombia, 2008. p. 85-86; FROMONT, op. cit., p. 220-221). La loi britannique est celle qui a le plus investi dans les procédures publiques, par le biais d'audiences publiques: “Incontestablement, c’est le droit britannique qui a donné le plus d’importance aux procédures publiques qui sont appelées enquêtes publiques. Ce qui caractérise les enquêtes, c’est que celles-ci commencent par des mesures de publicité permettant à l’ensemble des personnes intéressées de prendre part aux audiences qui sont ensuite organisées de façon contradictoire, selon un modèle quasi juridictionnel, mais qui ne portent en principe que sur la situation de fait du territoire concerné, ce qui permet ensuite à l’autorité administrative compétente de prendre en considération des objectifs qui dépassent le strict cadre territorial” (FROMONT, op. cit., p. 220). 112 À l'exemple du Règlement Intérieur du Tribunal des Comptes (Approuvé par la Résolution administrative n°15, en date du 15 Juin, 1993), aux arts. 161 et 281. 180 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. Cette évaluation peut aussi s'appliquer à la législation brésilienne concernant la procédure administrative. Cependant, il est possible d'avoir la sensation que, dans la société brésilienne, les droits subjectifs ne sont pas respectés par l'Administration,113 et que le Pouvoir Judiciaire est lent et incapable de répondre à la hauteur de ce qui est attendu de lui. 114 En réalité, les données statistiques indiquent l'existence d'un nombre croissant de conflits impliquant l'Administration115 et, proportionnellement, une augmentation de la durée de conclusion des procès ,116 bien que, paradoxalement, les structures juridictionnelles ne cessent de croître, et 113 Comme il en ressort de l'étude réalisée par le CNJ Justiça em números, les causes découlant d'une relation juridique de droit public, ayant comme demandeur ou défendeur les Pouvoirs Publics, représentent une majorité absolue des cas portés devant les tribunaux. "Justiça em números" est un système, comme indiqué sur le site du CNJ , qui vise l’élargissement du processus de connaissance du Pouvoir Judiciaire par le biais du prélèvement et de la systématisation de données statistiques et du calcul des indicateurs statistiques décrivant la performance des tribunaux. Dans le cas précis de cette étude, il est important de connaître le profil des demandes et de chercher à déterminer la participation du gouvernement dans les actions en justice, le contentieux et la quantité de travail, considérant la quantité de nouveaux cas, l'accumulation de travail du magistrat, le taux de congestionnement de la justice, la quantité de recours externes et internes et le taux de réformation des décisions. Selon les données recueillies par le CNJ pour l'année de référence 2009, les Pouvoirs Publics ont porté devant la Justice Fédérale de 1er degré, un total de 3.458.831 (trois millions quatre-cent cinquante huit mille huit-cent trente et un) de nouveaux cas. Dans cet ensemble , sont inclus les cinq tribunaux régionaux et les actions en justice de l'Union, des municipalités, des fondations et des entreprises publiques fédérales, des États, du District fédéral, des municipalités, des fondations et des États et des districts des entreprises publiques de l'État et des districts, des communes, des municipalités, des fondations et des entreprises publiques municipales. Un total de 2.580.232 (deux millions, cinq-cent quatre-vingt mille deux-cent trente deux) actions ont été portées devant la justice de 1º degré à l'encontre des Pouvoirs Publics. En ce qui concerne les actions en justice de 2ème degré, les Pouvoirs Publics ont porté en justice un total de 740 818 actions (sept-cent quarante mille huit-cent dix-huit) a contrario 676 966 (six-cent soixante-seize mille neuf-cent soixante six) ont été portées contre lui. Devant les tribunaux des Etats fédérés, les Pouvoirs Publics, en tant que demandeurs, ont atteint un total de 4.126.159 (quatre millions cent vingt-six mille cent cinquante neuf) actions, en précisant que, comme indiqué sur le site, certains Etats de la Fédération ne disposant pas de toutes les données, il peut être conclu que le résultat réel est plus élevé que celui susmentionné. Dans ce nombre, sont compris les deux degrés de juridiction. Devant les tribunaux des États fédérés ce sont 1.134.963 (un million cent trente quatre mille neuf- cent soixante trois) demandes au total ont été déposées contre les Pouvoirs Publics en 2009. 114 MATSUURA, Lilian. Para brasileiro, Justiça é lenta, cara e parcial. Consultor Jurídico, 22 fev. 2009. 115 Cette affirmation peut être démontrée par une étude menée par le Département de Recherches Judiciaires du Conseil National de la Justice ayant pour but d'identifier ceux qui avaient intenté le plus d'actions en justice (les 100 premiers) auprès des tribunaux des Etats fédérés, des tribunaux régionaux fédéraux et des tribunaux du travail. Il a été démontré que l'Institut National de Sécurité Sociale (INSS) est l'objet de plus d'un cinquième des actions en justice du classement total. Le secteur Public Fédéral est en tête en ce qui concerne le nombre de litiges, avec un total de 38,5%, suivi par le Secteur Public des Etats fédérés, avec un pourcentage de 7,8%, et un total de 5,2% pour le Secteur Municipal, soit un total 51,5% pour les entités de l'Administration Publique. Cela signifie que l'Union, les États, les Communes, les organismes municipaux et les fondations, soit au total environ 20 entités, (trois) personnes juridiques de droit public et 15 personnes juridiques de l'administration indirecte, atteignent un plus grand nombre de demandes que les 80 premiers plaideurs du pays, figurant parmi eux l'ensemble des secteurs de la banque et des télécommunications. Données disponibles sur le site: . Consulté le: 3 Juin 2011 (Moraes, Vânila Cardoso de. Demandas repetitivas decorrentes de ações ou omissões da Administração Pública: hipóteses de soluções e a necessidade de um direito processual público fundamentado na Constituição. la .En 2011. 231 f. Mémoire (Master en Justice Administrative) - Université Fédérale Fluminense, Niterói, RJ, 2011). 116 «(...) la 2ème instance de la Justice Fédérale, en particulier le TRF (Tribunal Régional Fédéral) de la 1ère Région, n'est pas en mesure, malgré la mise en oeuvre des processus d'amélioration de la gestion des procédures, 181 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. qu’il en est de même des dépenses.117 C'est le symptôme qui indique que quelque chose ne fonctionne pas bien. En effet, il y a un écart ou un décalage temporel entre la législation et la réalité de l'Administration Publique brésilienne. J'ai essayé de démontrer que la plupart des conflits dérivent, parfois par méconnaissance, d'une résistance de l'Administration à se conformer aux principes fondamentaux énoncés dans les normes de procédure administrative, qui constituent l'épine dorsale du droit administratif. Au Brésil, encore aujourd’hui, 15 ans après la publication de la Loi Générale de Procédure Administrative (Loi nº 9.784) et 25 ans après la promulgation de la Constitution, nous vivons avec une Administration qui date de l’époque où les actes administratifs étaient pris sans permettre l’exercice préalable des droits de la défense ou du contradictoire. Le manque généralisé d’anticipation des fonctionnaires publics a pu être notoirement constaté au moment de l’entrée en vigueur de la nouvelle loi relative à l’accès aux informations. Les journaux, y compris les publications du gouvernement, informaient alors de la surprise des fonctionnaires publics “qu’est-ce que c’est que cette loi d’accès aux informations ?”118 14 CONSIDÉRATIONS FINALES de raccourcir les délais de jugement. Au contraire, ces délais s'étendent, résulte de ce constat la preuve irréfutable de la stabilité ou même de l'augmentation au fil des ans, du congestionnement de l'appareil judiciaire, comme indiqué ci-dessous: TRIBUNAL 2004 TRF (moyenne) 67,1% TRF de la 1ère Région fédérale 69% Données obtenues à partir du site Web du CNJ et constant dans Cartilha Novos Tribunais: uma questão de Justiça, organisé par l'Association des Juges Fédéraux de Minas Gerais (AJUFEMG), Novembre 2010.(ASSOCIATION DES JUGES FÉDÉRAUX de MINAS GERAIS - AJUFEMG (Brésil).Cartilha Novos Tribunais: uma questão de justiça. Minas Gerais: AJUFEMG, 2010. p. 34). Taux de congestionnement: nombre de procédures qui sont entrées dans le système et qui n'ont pas été jugées . Notez qu'une grande partie de cette augmentation se doit au changement de la méthodologie adoptée par le CNJ, entre les années 2008 et 2009, s'agissant du calcul du taux de congestionnement » (Moraes, op. cit.). 117 Depuis 1989, la Justice Fédérale de 1ère instance a augmenté 470%, étant présente dans plus de 214 municipalités. Grâce à la loi n ° 12.011/2009, plus de 230 chambres fédérales ont été créées et leur installation se concluera entre 2010 à 2014, élevant cette croissance à un taux de 606% et à 273 municipalités. (ASSOCIATION DES JUGES FÉDÉRAUX DE MINAS - AJUFEMG (Brésil). Cartilha Novos Tribunais: uma questão de justiça, op. cit.). 118 BRUNO, Cássio; BASTOS, Isabela; CASTRO, Juliana; RAMALHO, Sérgio. Que lei de acesso é essa?, reage uma servidora. O Globo, le 17 mai 2012. http://www.cnj.jus.br/ 182 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. Dans ce contexte d’adversités, de culture et de mentalité issues du passé, je trouverais précipité voire même téméraire, dans un premier temps, d’accroître le pouvoir de l’Administration en matière de résolution des contentieux administratifs, en restreignant ou en admettant l’accès à la Justice à titre seulement subsidiaire. Mais je reconnais qu’à moyen terme, le perfectionnement des « autorités administratives indépendantes » est la voie naturelle. Toutefois, nous avons besoin d’une réforme, cependant elle ne porterait à ce stade sur le Pouvoir Judiciaire ou la législation processuelle administrative (juridictionnelle et non contentieuse), mais sur la propre Administration ; une réforme urgente qui concernerait notamment la qualification et la formation des agents publics, sur les aspects techniques et éthiques, permettant de lutter contre la corruption et qui conduise à une Administration efficace, crédible et renforcée telle un véritable troisième pouvoir. Nous avons besoin d’une réforme qui conduise à une Administration qui ne se cacherait pas derrière l’application stricte du principe de légalité, délégant par commodité au Pouvoir Judiciaire la reconnaissance de droits trouvant leur source dans la Constitution et dans les Conventions Internationales des Droits de l’Homme. Et finalement, nous avons besoin d’une réforme qui conduise à une Administration engagée en faveur de l’Etat de Droit, qui sans s’appuyer sur le Pouvoir Judiciaire, dispose de l’initiative d’assurer les droits fondamentaux. RÉFÉRENCES ALLEMAGNE. Bundesverfassungsgerichts (BverfGE). BVerfGE 33, 1. Entscheidungen des Bundesverfassungsgerichts (BverfGE). Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 16 juil. 2012. ______. Verwaltungsgerichtsordnung (VwGO). Code de Juridiction Administrative. Loi du 21 janvier 1960 (BGBl. I S. 17), modifiée et nouvellement promulguée le 19 mars 1991 (BGBl. I S. 686), actualisée selon les altérations imposées par l’article 3 de la Loi du 21 décembre 2006 (BGBl. I S. 3316) et par l’article 13 de la Loi du 12 décembre 2007 (BGBl. I S. 2840). Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ______. Verwaltungsverfahrensgesetz (VwVfG). Code allemand de procédures administratives du 25 mai 1976. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ARGENTINE. Constitución Nacional. Sancionada por el congreso general constituyente el 1° de mayo de 1853, reformada y concordada por la convención nacional ad hoc el 25 de 183 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. septiembre de 1860 y con las reformas de las convenciones de 1866, 1898, 1957 y 1994. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ______. Ley Contencioso Administrativo de la Província de Buenos Aires. Ley nº 12.008 de 01 de junio de 1999. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ASSOCIATION DES JUGES FÉDÉRAUX DE MINAS GERAIS – AJUFEMG (Brésil). Cartilha Novos Tribunais: uma questão de justiça. Minais Gerais: AJUFEMG, 2010. AUTRICHE. Bundes-Verfassungsgesetz (B-VG). Constitution du 1o octobre 1920. Disponible sur le site: < http://www.verfassungen.de/at/ >. Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. BELGIQUE. Constitution Belge. Constitution de 1993. Texte coordonné le 17 février 1994. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ______. Loi du 23 décembre 1946 – Loi du Conseil d’État de Belgique. Loi du 23 décembre 1946. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. BRÉSIL. Código de Organização e Divisão Judiciárias do Estado do Rio de Janeiro. Actualisé le 27 avril 2011. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ______. Conselho Nacional de Justiça (Conseil National de Justice). Justiça em números. Dados colhidos no ano-base de 2009. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ______. Superior Tribunal de Justiça. (Tribunal Supérieur de Justice). Regimento interno. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. BREWER-CARÍAS, Allan. Bases constitucionales del derecho administrativo. In: Estudios de derecho administrativo 2005-2007. Caracas: Editorial Jurídica Venezuelana, 2007. ______. Principios del procedimiento administrativo en América Latina. Bogotá: Legis, 2003. BRUNO, Cássio; BASTOS, Isabela; CASTRO, Juliana; RAMALHO, Sérgio. Que lei de acesso é essa?, reage uma servidora. O Globo, 17 mai 2012. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 15 juin 2012. CHILI. Codigo Organico de Tribunales. Ley nº 7.421, de 15 de junio de 1943. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. 184 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. CODE de Procédure Administrative allemand. Traduction et annotations Alberto Augusto Andrade de Oliveira. Coimbra: Livraria da Universidade – DL, 1996. COLOMBIE. Constitución Política de Colombia. Constitution Politique de Colombie, du 20 juillet 1991. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ______. Ley nº 1.437, de 18 de enero de 2011. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. COSTA RICA. Código Procesal Contencioso-Administrativo. Ley nº 8.508, de 1º de enero de 2008. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ______. Constitucion Politica de la Republica de Costa Rica de 1949. Actualizada hasta Ley n° 8.365, del 15 de julio del 2003. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ______. Ley Organica del Poder Judicial. Ley nº 7.333/1993, modificada por la Ley nº 7.728, de 15 de diciembre de 1997. Disponible sur le site: < http://www.tse.go.cr/pdf/normativa/leyorganicapoderjudicial.pdf >. Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. GARCÍA DE ENTERRÍA, Eduardo. La lucha contra las inmunidades del poder. 3. ed. Madri: Civitas, 1995. ______; FERNÁNDEZ, Tomás-Ramón. Curso de direito administrativo. Traduction Arnaldo Setti. São Paulo: Revista dos Tribunais, 1991. ESPAGNE. Constitución Española, de 29 de diciembre de 1978. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ______. Ley nº 23, de 7 de julio de 1998. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. FORSTHOFF, Ernst. Tratado de derecho administrativo. Traduction Legaz Lacambra, Garrido Falla et Gómez de Ortega y Junge. Madri: Instituto de Estudios Politicos, 1958. FRANCE. Code de Justice Administrative. Dernière modification le 20 juin 2012. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. FROMONT, Michel. Droit administratif des Etats européens. Paris: PUF, 2006. GRÈCE. Νομοθετικού διατάγματος [Ν] 170/1973. Décret Législatif nº 170/1973, rectifié par les Lois nº 702/1977 et nº 1470/1984 et codifié par le Décret nº 18/1989. Disponible sur le http://www.tse.go.cr/pdf/normativa/leyorganicapoderjudicial.pdf 185 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ______. Πράξη 1406/1983. Loi no 1.406 de 1983. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ______. Σύνταγμα της Ελλάδας. Constitution du 9 juin 1975. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. HONGRIE. Bírósági szervezet szóló 1997. Loi de L’Organisation Judiciaire de 1997. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. INSTITUTO IBERO-AMERICANO DE DIREITO PROCESSUAL. (Institut Ibéro- Américain de Droit Processuel) Código Modelo de Processos Administrativos – Judicial e Extrajudicial – para Ibero-América. Buenos Aires: IIDP, 2012. Disponible sur le site: < http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2250852 >. Consulté le: 16 juin. 2012. ITALIE. Costituzione della Repubblica Italiana, de 27 de dicembre de 1947. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ______. Legge 27 aprile 1982, n. 186. Loi nº 186, du 27 avril 1982. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. MATSUURA, Lilian. Para brasileiro, Justiça é lenta, cara e parcial. Consultor Jurídico, 22 fév. 2009. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 16 juin. 2012. MAURER, Hartmut. Direito administrativo geral. Barueri: Manole, 2006. MAYER, Otto. Derecho administrativo alemán. Buenos Aires: Depalma, 1982. t. I. MELLO, Celso Antônio Bandeira de. Curso de direito administrativo. 21. ed. São Paulo: Malheiros, 2006. MÉXIQUE. Constitucion Política de los Estados Unidos Mexicanos, de 5 de febrero de 1917. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ______. Ley Orgánica del Tribunal Federal de Justicia Fiscal y Administrativa. Dernière réforme publiée le 3 juin 2011. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. MEYER, Hans. El procedimiento administrativo en la Republica Federal de Alemania. In: VAZQUEZ, Javier Barnés (Org.). El procedimento administrativo en el derecho comparado. Madri: Civitas, 1993. 186 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. MIRANDA, Henrique Savonitti. Licitações e contratos administrativos. Brésilia: Escola Nacional de Administração Pública (École Nationale de l’Administration Publique), 2004. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 19 avr. 2011. MORAES, Vânila Cardoso Andre de. Demandas repetitivas decorrentes de ações ou omissões da Administração Pública: hipóteses de soluções e a necessidade de um direito processual público fundamentado na Constituição. 2011. 231 f. Mémoire (Master en Justice Administrative) – Université Fédérale Fluminense, Niterói, RJ, 2011. Disponible sur le site: < http://www2.cjf.jus.br/ojs2/index.php/mono/index >. Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. PAYS-BAS. Wet van 9 maart 1962, op de Raad van State. Loi du 9 mars 1962. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. PERLINGEIRO, Ricardo. A impugnação judicial de atos administrativos na defesa de interesses difusos, coletivos e individuais homogêneos. In: XXVIII Congreso Colombiano De Derecho Procesal. Bogotá: Universidad Libre, p. 919-938, 2007. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 5 juil. 2013. ______. O princípio da isonomia na tutela judicial individual e coletiva, e em outros meios de solução de conflitos, junto ao SUS e aos planos privados de saúde. In: NOBRE, Milton; DIAS, Ricardo (Orgs.). O Conselho Nacional de Justiça e os desafios da efetivação do direito à saúde. Belo Horizonte: Fórum, 2011. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 5 juil. 2013. ______; BLANKE, Hermann-Josef; SOMMERMANN, Karl-Peter (Coords.). Código de jurisdição administrativa: o modelo alemão. Rio de Janeiro: Renovar, 2009. PÉROU. Constitucion Politica del Peru de 1993. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ______. Ley del Procedimiento Administrativo General. Lei nº 27.444, de 10 avril 2001. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. POCHARD, Marcel. La Administración Pública y la protección de los derechos fundamentales. In: CONSEJO DE ESTADO DE LA REPÚBLICA DE COLOMBIA. Seminario Franco-Colombiano sobre la Reforma a la Jurisdicción Contencioso Administrativa. Bogotá: Imprenta Nacional de Colombia, 2008. PORTUGAL. Código de Processo nos Tribunais Administrativos. Loi nº 4-A, du 19 février 2003. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ______. Constituição da República Portuguesa, de 2 de abril de 1976. (Constitution de la République Portugaise du 2 avril 1976). Revision VII de 2005. Disponible sur le site: http://www2.cjf.jus.br/ojs2/index.php/mono/index http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2250854 http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2241142 http://www.unmsm.edu.pe/ogp/ARCHIVOS/LEY%20DEL%20PROCEDIMIENTO%20ADMINISTRATIVO.htm http://www.unmsm.edu.pe/ogp/ARCHIVOS/LEY%20DEL%20PROCEDIMIENTO%20ADMINISTRATIVO.htm 187 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ______. Estatuto dos Tribunais Administrativos e Fiscais. Loi nº 13, du 31 janvier 2002. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ROCHA, Carmen Lúcia Antunes. Princípios constitucionais do processo administrativo no Direito brasileiro. Revista de Informação Legislativa, Brésilia: Sénat Fédéral, anné 34, n. 136, p. 5-28, oct./déc. 1997. SADEK, Maria Teresa. Judiciário e arena pública: um olhar a partir da ciência política. In: GRINOVER, Ada Pellegrini; WATANABE, Kazuo (Org.). O controle jurisdicional de políticas públicas. 1. ed. Rio de Janeiro: Forense, 2011. SCHMIDT-AβMANN, E. Sobre el objeto del procedimiento administrativo em la dogmática administrativa alemana. In: VAZQUEZ, Javier Barnés (Org.). El procedimento administrativo en el derecho comparado. Madri: Civitas, 1993. SIRINELLI, Jean. Les transformations du droit administratif par le droit de l’Union Européenne. Paris: LGDJ, 2011. SUÈDE. Författning 1974. Constitution de 1974. Approuvée le 1o janvier 1975. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. SUISSE. Bundesgerichtsgesetz, BGG. Loi du 17 juin 2005. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ______. Bundesgesetz über das Verwaltungsverfahren. Loi du 20 décembre 1968. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. __________. Verfassung der Schweiz. Constitution approuvée par le référendum du 12 mars 2000. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. UNIVERSIDADE FEDERAL FLUMINENSE. (Université Fédérale Fluminense). Núcleo de Ciências do Poder Judiciário (Centre des Sciences du Pouvoir Judiciaire). Projeto Acadêmico do Programa de Pós-Graduação Justiça Administrativa (Projet Académique du Programme de Post-grade en Justice Administrative)- PPGJA-UFF. Niterói, 2008. VENEZUELA. Constitución de la República Bolivariana de Venezuela de 1999. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. WOLFF, Hans J.; BACHOF, Otto; STOBER, Rolf. Direito administrativo. Traduction Antônio F. de Sousa. Lisboa: Fundação Calouste Gulbenkian, 2006. ZAFFARONI, Eugenio Raúl. Poder Judiciário. São Paulo: Revista dos Tribunais, 1995. ZILLER, Jacques. Administrations comparées. Les systèmes politico-administratifs de l’Europe des Douze. Paris: Montchrestien, 1993. 188 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. PRÉCÉDENTS JUDICIAIRES BRÉSIL. Supremo Tribunal Federal (Cour Suprême Fédérale). AI 59.7182. 2ª Classe. Rapporteur min. Cezar Peluso. Brésilia, DF. Publié le: 6 nov. 2006. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ______. Supremo Tribunal Federal. (Cour Suprême Fédérale). AI 64.1911, AgR. 1ª Classe. Rapporteur min. Cármen Lúcia. Brésilia, DF. Publié le: 1o oct. 2009. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ______. Supremo Tribunal Federal. (Cour Suprême Fédérale). AI 685-866-AgR. Rapporteur min. Ricardo Lewandowski. Brésilia, DF. Publié le: 22 mai 2009. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ______. Supremo Tribunal Federal. (Cour Suprême Fédérale). MS 25.787-3/DF. Rapporteur min. Gilmar Mendes. Brésilia, DF. Publié le: 14 sept. 2007. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ______. Supremo Tribunal Federal. (Cour Suprême Fédérale). RE 116.683. Rapporteur min. Celso de Mello. Brésilia, DF. Publié le: 13 mar. 1993. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ______. Supremo Tribunal Federal. (Cour Suprême Fédérale). SL 47 AgR. Pleno. Rapporteur min. Gilmar Mendes. Brésilia, DF. Publié le: 30 avr. 2010. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ______. Supremo Tribunal Federal. (Cour Suprême Fédérale). Súmula Vinculante nº 3. Session Plénière, 30 mai 2007. Brésilia, DF. Publié le: 6 juin 2007. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ______. Tribunal de Contas da União. (Cour des Comptes de l’Union). Regimento interno. Approuvé par la Résolution Administrative nº 246, du 30 novembre 2011. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ______. Tribunal de Contas da União. (Cour des Comptes de l’Union). Acórdão 2.553/2009. Session Plénière. Rapporteur min. José Jorge. Brésilia, DF. Publié le: 4 nov. 2009. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. 189 Revista Juris Poiesis - Rio de Janeiro. Vol.22-n°28, 2019, pg.157-189. ISSN 2448-0517 Rio de Janeiro, 29 de abril de 2019. ______. Tribunal Regional Federal da 2ª Região. (Tribunal Régional Fédéral de la 2º Région). AG 201102010109190. 5a Classe. Rapporteur juge Ricardo Perlingeiro. Publié le fév. 2012. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. ______. Tribunal Regional Federal da 2ª Região. (Tribunal Régional Fédéral de la 2º Région). Regimento interno. Diário da Justiça da União, du 29 janvier 2009. Actualisé jusqu’à l’Altération au Règlement nº 26, du 14 mai 2012. Disponible sur le site: . Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. CORTE INTERAMERICANA DE DIREITOS HUMANOS. Caso Radilla Pacheco vs. México. Excepciones Preliminares, Fondo, Reparaciones y Costas. Sentencia de 23 de Noviembre de 2009. Serie C No. 209. Disponible sur le site: < http://www.ordenjuridico.gob.mx/JurInt/STCIDHM4.pdf >. Consulté le: 12 juil. 2012. Submetido em: 20/02/2019 Aceito em: 27/03/2019 work_cmhqxj426jftpjnuv4ggjmn75e ---- PII: 0047-2352(90)90018-7 Jourml of Criminal Justice Vol. 18, pp. 33-41 (1990) All rights reserved. Printed in U.S.A. 0047-23x/90 $3.00 + .oo Copyright 0 1990 Pergamon Press plc Evaluating Criminal Justice Programs: Establishing Criteria TOMAS MIJARES Detroit Police Department and Criminal Justice Department Detroit, Michigan 48221 ROBERT BLACKBURN Center for the Study of Higher and Postsecondary Education University of Michigan Ann Arbor, Michigan 48109 ABSTRACT Directors of 239 four-year undergraduate criminal justice programs in the United States were asked to nominate the outstanding programs in that country and to state the criteria upon which they made their assessment. Eleven criteria and twenty-four institutions were mentioned by four or more directors. Institutional data produced moderate correlations between the frequency of mention and many of the indicators for the criteria. Similarities and differences with quality criteria found in ratings of more established fields of study are discussed. PROBLEM/OBJECTIVES Reliance on higher education as a means of legitimizing newly emerging professions has been discussed extensively in the litera- ture of higher education. As a relatively new academic discipline, with beginnings not un- like business administration, engineering, and nursing, criminal justice education has al- ready been the subject of several comprehen- sive studies (Pearson, Moran, Berger, Lau- don, McKenzie, and Bonita, 1967; Tenney, 1971; Sherman, 1978; Ward and Webb, 1984). Although the studies may have approached the topic from differing philosophical per- spectives and they may have differed also in their purposes, data-collection and analysis methods, and in many of their conclusions about the value and efficacy of criminal jus- tice education programs, they were unani- mous in their recommendations for further and continuous research on both the product and delivery system of criminal justice education. To understand why a program is consid- ered “good,” the present authors attempted to establish criteria for such judgments by sur- veying chair-people of undergraduate pro- grams in criminal justice. Criticisms of com- parative studies of academic programs were taken into account. Understandably, subjects (deans, program directors, faculty members, etc.) who are not highly rated tend to be crit- ical of a study regardless of the care and thor- oughness with which it was undertaken. An 33 34 TOMAS MIJARES and ROBERT BLACKBURN attempt was made to mitigate this criticism by employing a two-part open-ended ques- tionnaire, which asked: “What are the lead- ing criminal justice education programs’?” and “What are the criteria that determine their relative status?” Thus, respondents were al- lowed to identify the factors by which they determine excellence. Although some dis- agreement over rankings is inevitable, the au- thors hope readers will realize that reputa- tional studies are necessarily based on the perceptions held by peers. The purpose of this study was not to conduct a popularity contest but to enhance understanding of the qualities raters use to form their impressions of ex- cellence. In addition, the reader must rec- ognize that frequency of mention is not an absolute indicator of quality. A program mentioned twenty times is not necessarily twice as good as a program mentioned ten times. In addition, even those not mentioned can be quality programs. METHODOLOGY As of 1988, excluding associate-degree criminal justice programs in two-year colleges and schools with only graduate programs, 215 programs have remained in operation in the United States since the termination of the Law Enforcement Education Program (L.E.E.P.). The director of each of these pro- grams (dean, department chairperson, etc.) was invited to nominate and rank the top ten undergraduate programs in the country’ and to describe what it was that made each of those programs distinctive.* After thirty-six respon- dents who said they did not know enough about programs across the country to rank them (persons new in their positions or from small, isolated programs) were dropped from the analysis, 112 (56 percent) criminal jus- tice department directors supplied all or part of the requested information.’ The second phase of the study involved identifying the descriptive variables used by the directors in making their rankings.” In the third phase a questionnaire was sent request- ing information on institutional characteris- tics from the twenty-four programs that re- ceived the highest number of nominations. DATA Seventy-nine programs were listed at least once. Four were mentioned fifty-six to sixty- five times and constitute a distinct cluster at the top. One program was nominated thirty- eight times. It stands alone, for the next most frequently mentioned program was named nineteen times. Twenty-four programs were mentioned four or more times by the 1 12 di- rectors. These twenty-four constitute the data base for the analysis. Table 1 lists the insti- tutions by ranking and identifies the criteria established by the respondents for each ranking. Eleven other schools were listed three times, twenty-one were mentioned twice, and twenty- three were cited once. These fifty-five schools were excluded from further study because, when the nominations are so few, there is in- sufficient data with which to make compar- isons. The twenty-four programs mentioned four or more times provided a wide enough range to test variable relationships. RESULTS Criteria Content analysis produced eleven factors (variables) associated with more highly rated institutions. They were (1) general reputa- tion; (2) faculty credentials (quality of uni- versity from which the final degree was earned); (3) faculty research production; (4) curriculum (quality and breadth of course of- ferings); (5) public service; (6) professional- association activity; (7) coexistence of grad- uate study; (8) resources and physical facil- ities; (9) quality and number of students en- rolled; (IO) size of the program; and ( 11) age (number of years in existence). Each of the factors correlated highly with the number of times the institution was men- tioned as a leader in the field. Four had Pear- son r values over .90: curriculum, faculty credentials, faculty research production, and T A B L E 1 C H A R A C T E R IS T IC S O F H IG H L Y R A T E D C R IM IN A L J U S T IC E P R O G R A M S In st it u ti o n s C ri te ri a A B C D E F G H IJ K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X T o ta l * (6 5 ) (5 9 ) (5 6 ) (5 6 ) (3 8 ) (1 9 ) (1 9 ) (1 7 ) (1 6 ) (1 5 ) (1 4 ) (1 4 ) (1 2 ) (1 2 ) (1 1 ) (1 0 ) (9 ) (9 ) (8 ) (7 ) (6 ) (5 ) (4 ) (4 ) G en er al re pu ta ti on 20 15 17 15 12 5 3 2 5 5 7 7 3 5 2 2 4 5 5 3 3 0 2 2 14 9 F ac ul ty cr ed en ti al s 37 38 35 21 30 19 14 16 9 13 10 8 9 8 6 7 6 5 4 1 3 4 0 30 4 R es ea rc h 21 21 15 20 14 6 0 7 7 4 4 4 2 5 6 4 1 1 0 1 1 1 0 : 14 7 C ur ri cu lu m 10 16 10 15 8 6 4 2 3 2 0 4 3 0 1 1 1 3 0 1 1 0 0 0 91 P ub li c se rv ic e 2 2 1 3 1 1 1 2 1 1 0 0 0 1 1 1 1 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 20 A ss oc ia ti on ac ti vi ty 3 2 3 2 0 0 2 2 0 0 1 1 1 1 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 19 G ra du at e sc ho ol 7 6 5 7 5 1 0 1 3 0 1 0 4 0 1 1 1 1 0 1 0 1 0 47 S iz e 5 3 4 3 1 0 2 0 0 2 0 0 1 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 : 22 R es ea rc h a n d fa ci li ti es 4 4 8 1 3 0 0 1 0 2 0 1 0 1 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 2 0 28 S tu de nt s 14 23 8 8 4 8 4 6 1 3 0 4 1 2 0 2 1 2 2 0 0 0 tl 0 93 A g e 10 3 1 3 1 16 00 01 00 20 21 10 ~ 2~ ~ ~ 34 * T h e nu m be r of ti m es in st it ut io ns A (B , C , D , .) w er e m en ti on ed by th e ra te rs 36 TOMAS MIJARES and ROBERT BLACKBURN general reputation. The lowest correlation was for age of the program, r = .62 (see Table 2). In a multiple regression, the multiple R and the R* for the variables predicting fre- quency of mention (excellence, quality) were over .99. Scholarly Training Relationships Scholarly training of the faculty is fre- quently used as an indicator of program qual- ity. Having a doctorate is one indicator of ad- vanced training. Consequently, the percentage of the faculty with doctorates was examined. Second, professional experience allows fac- ulty members immediate access to agency data banks that nonprofessionals have difficulty gaining. Use of such actual data promotes an application of theoretical information. Thus, the percentage of faculty members with agency experience was also used as an indicator of quality. Third, since full-time faculty mem- bers are more able to devote their time and resources to academic matters, such as coun- seling students and conducting research, than are part-time faculty members, the percent- age of full-time faculty members was used as an indicator of faculty quality. Moderate relationships were found be- tween program rating and two of the three measures of faculty quality (percentage of faculty members with agency experience: r = .37, and the percentage of full-time faculty members: r = .37). No significant relation- ship was found between program ranking and the percentage of doctorates (r = .05). Sig- nificant differences were evident between the top twenty-four programs and the remaining 21.5 in each of the measures. Over sixty-two percent of the faculty members of the top twenty-four had doctoral degrees while only thirty-three percent of the remaining 21.5 had them. Similarly, fifty-three percent of the faculty members of the top twenty-four had worked in criminal justice agencies while only thirty-six percent from the remaining 2 15 had done so. Over seventy-five percent of the faculty members of the top twenty-four had full-time appointments while only fifty-two percent of the faculty members of the re- maining 215 programs were full-time. Research Productivity Research production has long been consid- ered an accurate indicator of program quality in several disciplines. One of the most readily employed measures of research production is published journal articles (Garfield, 1972). The relationship between an institution’s rank among the top twenty-four programs and the number of journal articles published by its faculty (r < . 10) failed to achieve significance. In view of the absence of a relationship be- tween rank and this quantitative measure, more inferential methods were employed. A Ph.D. from a research university generally indicates a proclivity toward scholarly activity. No sig- nificant frequency relationship was found, however, between being rated among the top twenty-four programs and the percentage of faculty with such degrees from scholar-pro- ducing universities (r < .lO). Because full- time faculty members are more likely to con- duct research (MaGarrell, 1978), it could also be hypothesized that the percentage of full- time faculty members should correlate with being rated among the top twenty-four pro- grams. Although this correlation was mod- erately positive (r = .37), there was no sig- nificant relationship between the percentage of full-time faculty and the number of articles published over a three-year period (r < 10). The lack of journal articles published by criminal justice faculty members and the ac- companying lack of significant comparisons suggest that the traditional measures of re- search production are currently not effective for assessing quality in this field. The crea- tive criminal justice faculty research efforts are being channeled into other activities. A review of the faculty vitae from six of the top twenty-four programs indicated that these ed- ucators participated in the following activities: 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. editing books writing textbooks for use by students writing textbooks for use by professionals assuming leadership roles in professional associations conducting and participating in conferences and symposia writing grants writing agency grants T A B L E 2 C O R R E L A T IO N S O F D E T E R M IN A N T S O F P R O G R A M Q U A L IT Y R es ou rc es F ac u lt y F ac u lt y an d F ac u lt y F ac u lt y P u bl ic A ss oc ia ti on G ra du at e P h ys ic al N u m be r o f P ro gr am F re qu en cy R ep u ta ti on C re de n ti al s R es ea rc h C u rr ic u lu m S er vi ce A ct iv it y P ro gr am S iz e F ac il it ie s S tu de n ts A ge F re q u en cy 1 .0 0 0 0 R ep u ta ti on .9 4 1 5 l. O C Q O F a cu lt y c re d en ti a ls .9 3 8 5 .8 5 1 5 1 .0 0 0 0 F a cu lt y r es ea rc h .9 4 5 8 .8 5 1 9 .8 9 8 0 1 .0 0 0 0 C u rr ic u lu m .9 3 3 7 .8 4 6 5 .8 6 5 1 .8 9 6 1 1 .0 0 0 0 F a cu lt y p u b li c se rv ic e .7 2 8 7 .6 1 9 4 .6 4 8 9 .7 3 2 5 .7 2 6 7 1 .0 0 0 0 F a cu lt y a ss oc ia ti on a ct iv it y .7 6 9 4 .7 0 0 3 .7 0 9 5 .6 4 3 5 .6 4 0 1 .6 0 6 3 l. O O oO G ra d u a te p ro g ra m .8 9 5 4 .8 2 5 1 .8 0 6 2 .8 9 6 8 .8 6 4 7 .6 2 9 0 .5 9 6 9 1 .0 0 0 0 S iz e .8 9 4 4 .8 1 8 4 .8 2 4 3 .7 9 1 5 .7 8 0 0 .5 9 6 6 .7 6 2 4 .7 7 0 2 1 .0 0 0 0 R es ou rc es a n d p h y si ca l fa ci li ti es .7 5 8 5 .7 5 7 7 .7 8 1 9 .6 7 1 6 .6 2 1 3 .3 6 0 9 .6 1 7 5 .5 9 5 3 .7 4 4 8 1 .0 0 0 0 N u m b er o f st u d en ts .8 4 0 4 .7 5 5 9 .8 4 8 2 .7 9 7 6 ,8 5 9 s .6 7 8 8 .6 7 0 7 .6 7 5 5 .7 0 5 2 .6 0 1 7 1 .0 0 0 0 P ro g ra m a g e .6 1 9 4 .5 7 7 4 5 5 8 2 .5 1 1 6 .4 8 9 4 .5 0 4 6 .6 4 7 8 .4 7 5 9 .6 8 9 2 .2 9 6 4 .5 5 1 2 l. oo oO _ .A ~ . I - - - > v - ~ _ \_ _ _ r, , ., > s _ “_ -- - . _ - -_ _ _ -. ,. . _ - r, > - - TOMAS MIJARES and ROBERT BLACKBURN 38 8. 9. evaluating criminal-justice agency projects and operations supervising the implementation of criminal- justice agency projects and operations In addition, some schools have expanded the field’s body of knowledge through insti- tution-wide research programs. For example, the Office of International Criminal Justice at the University of Illinois-Chicago and sim- ilar programs at other leading schools con- tribute to the overall knowledge base. How- ever, participation in these programs requires such a commitment of time and resources that individual research projects must be post- poned, the immediate application of this knowledge is not presented through tradi- tional academic media, and the field does not enjoy the same degree of scholarly scrutiny, recognition, and prestige by scholars from other academic fields. Curriculum Quulity Researchers have employed a wide variety of means to measure curriculum quality, such as textbook examination (Sherman and McLeod, 1979) and syllabus review (Kuy- kendall and Hemandez, 1975). Relationships between program rank and the number of courses and degrees offered were not signif- icant. However, when course descriptions in school catalogs were examined, a recurring pattern was observed, in which each of the top twenty-four programs offered at least the undergraduate course in research methods (3.1 courses per school). In contrast, only 125 (59 percent) of the remaining 2 15 schools offered any coursework in research methods (less than one course per school). Public Service A measure of public-service activity by criminal justice faculty was obtained by ask- ing the program directors to indicate the number of hours donated by the entire de- partment per term. The range of responses was wide. Five of the directors gave no response, and the remaining responses were estimates. No significant relationship (r < . 10) was found between institutional rating and the number of hours donated in public service by mem- bers of the criminal justice department. (The absence of a relationship probably was less a function of the actual time donated by faculty and more a consequence of the absence of a consistent record-keeping system for the amount of time donated to public service.) Prqfessional Associations Association membership provides tangible benefits to the individual faculty member, to the institution, and to the field, particularly when this membership reflects office holding or scholarly activity sanctioned by these as- sociations. The activity level of criminal jus- tice faculty members in professional/aca- demic associations was assessed by asking the program directors to indicate by title the of- fices held by faculty members in profes- sional/academic organizations within the past five years. There was a moderate correlation (r = .43) between institutional rating and the number of association offices held by mem- bers of each criminal justice education program. Graduate Programs The coexistence of a graduate program was associated with institutional ranking. Twenty- one (88 percent) of the top twenty-four pro- grams granted a master’s degree and eleven (46 percent) granted the Ph.D. Within the top twenty-four, the first five granted the Ph.D., whereas only one of the bottom five in that group did so. In contrast, only seventy-nine (37 percent) of the remaining 2 15 programs granted the master’s degree and four (2 per- cent) granted the Ph.D. Or.gunizational Structure Organizational structure was highly asso- ciated with rating. The top seven programs existed as independent schools within their universities. The last seven of the top twenty- four programs (as well as all of the remaining 215 programs) were departments and had not received this level of autonomy. Evaluating Criminal Justice Programs: Establishing Criteria 39 Student Qualities Traditional discussions of the quality of students in higher education tend to focus on items such as secondary school preparation, SAT/ACT scores, number of students en- rolled and graduated, student/faculty ratios, and commuter/resident status (Chickering, 1974). Data provided by the program direc- tors indicated very little variation among the top twenty-four schools for these indicators. However, when the quality of in-service stu- dents was examined in terms of the relation- ship with career background, differences were found. In-service students (those already em- ployed by a criminal justice agency) in the lowest-ranked schools of the top twenty-four tended to come from the law-enforcement portion of the criminal justice system while in-service students from the most highly ranked schools tended to come from more di- verse backgrounds (i.e., they were more evenly distributed among law enforcement, courts, corrections, private security, and the military). However, the data submitted by the respondents were not sufficient to allow sta- tistical comparisons. Size Program size affects the amount of expo- sure to academic diversity, the number of grants, the richness of physical facilities, and public awareness of the program. The most easily measured elements of size are the number of students enrolled, the number of students graduated, the number of courses of- fered, and the number of faculty. A multiple correlation equation produced significant re- sults between institutional rating and these size factors (R = .9662 and R2 = .9335). A sig- nificant difference was found between the means of each of these measures for the twenty-four most frequently mentioned pro- grams and the corresponding means of these measures for the remaining 2 15 programs. Age The age of a program correlated moder- ately with institutional rating (r = .34). A more accurate picture was developed by comparing the top twenty-four to the remain- ing 2 15. Eighteen of the top twenty-four (75 percent) received the full twelve years of benefits of the Omnibus Crime Control and Safe Streets Act of 1968. The entire twenty- four received an average of 10.0 years of benefits. Only twenty-four of the remaining 215 (11 percent) were already in operation when the Act was passed. The remaining 191 received benefits for an average of eight years. The present authors feel that any vocational educational program that survives without governmental assistance during a period of declining employment possesses some of the criteria for excellence. DISCUSSION Three themes have emerged from this study. First, the responses from the participating program directors indicate that program qual- ity has a variety of components, many of which act in concert (see Table 2). Some of the same factors employed in correlate-qual- ity rating studies of traditional programs have appeared in this nascent field and do not show signs of changing over time. General repu- tation, faculty credentials, and faculty re- search production are significant factors in all studies of academic quality (Webster, 1986). On the other hand, the quality of curricu- lum, the amount of public-service time do- nated, the coexistence of a graduate program, the amount and type of professional-associ- ation activity performed by faculty members, and the commitment of resources to long-term operations are seldom considered in tradi- tional rating studies, yet they matter for crim- inal justice programs.5 By identifying, com- paring, and evaluating these variables, many of which are within institutional control, schools that were not mentioned with any measurable frequency in this study can make adjustments in their own programs, not solely for the sake of institutional prestige but also for the improvement of the field. Similarly, information provided by this study can help governmental regulatory and legislative bod- ies in the disbursement and control of funds. 40 TOMAS MIJARES and ROBERT BLACKBURN Second, the findings suggested that the participating program directors identified dif- ferences between the top twenty-four and the remaining 215 programs in variables that re- flect a commitment to research and the ex- pansion of the body of knowledge. In many instances, criminal justice faculty members have been hired because of whom they know rather than what they know and because of their professional experience rather than their academic credentials. Although faculty cre- dentials have been progressively improved since the implementation of the Omnibus Crime Control and Safe Streets Act of 1968, the lesser-ranked programs still have a dis- proportionate share of part-time faculty who do not possess the skills, motivation, or re- sources to engage in the generation of knowl- edge. Despite the fact that criminal justice educators as a group are not participating in journal publication as frequently as their counterparts in other disciplines, faculty from the top twenty-four programs have been di- recting their creative efforts into alternative channels. Other variables have demonstrated fur- ther the difference between the top twenty- four and the remaining 215 programs in the commitment to research. Differences in cur- ricula have already been discussed. The greater contributions to public service by faculty in the top twenty-four indicate a stronger inter- est in being close to real-world data. Their more frequent activity in professional asso- ciations indicates a difference in the approach to disseminating the growing body of knowl- edge through annual conventions and other sanctioned activities. Their selection of stu- dents with more diverse backgrounds indi- cates that they are more interested in design- ing programs that expose students to different perspectives than are faculty in programs de- signed for a more homogeneous student body. The propensity of the leading programs to operate graduate programs concurrently in- dicates an interest not only in expanding the body of knowledge but also in developing competent scholars. Finally, the trend among the top twenty-four to be organized as auton- omous schools instead of departments indi- cates a commitment to long-term growth and continuous operations instead of providing a temporary academic service based on the availability of governmental funding. The third theme emerging from the study is that when current data are put into an op- erational and historical perspective, their im- pact on program quality and on the discipline becomes even more apparent. Schools in the top twenty-four have initiated faculty devel- opment plans so more faculty members pos- sess the experience of the practitioner and the academic credentials of the scholar. Where earlier students were primarily in-service law- enforcement officers attending classes for a variety of nonscholarly reasons, the majority now consists of preservice students who in- tend to pursue careers in all phases of crim- inal justice. In addition, based on direct ex- perience and conversations with faculty at other institutions, it appears that many stu- dents who are not majors are registering for one or two criminal justice courses for the purpose of general education and/or related electives. Where coursework was originally designed to improve the job-related skills of in-service students, it has become more con- ceptual and is becoming more integrated with the rest of the academic community. Where public service in the academic sense was vir- tually nonexistent in the field, its importance is now recognized as an excellent source of data and ideas for research projects. Where association activity was limited to associate and honorary membership in organizations composed primarily of criminal-justice prac- titioners, faculty members are becoming in- creasingly more active in organizations, such as the Academy of Criminal Justice Sciences and the American Society of Criminology, in which they can disseminate the fruits of their research. Where resources and facilities were initially developed for a quick profit in the true entrepreneurial spirit, the top twenty-four have concerned themselves more with long- term growth. Although the field must mature in each of the factors contributing to program excellence, the criticism directed at criminal justice in the mid-1970s was not unlike that directed to other fledgling disciplines. Evaluating Criminal Justice Programs: Establishing Criteria 41 RECOMMENDATIONS FOR FURTHER STUDY Without the social changes in American society and the attendant federal funding dur- ing the 196Os, criminal justice studies would not have experienced such a rapid growth. Further studies need to evaluate the effect of the educational process on the areas ad- dressed by the authors of the legislation fos- tering this growth. Particular attention must be paid to the use of higher education as a crime-fighting tool by preparing more effec- tive criminal-justice personnel. Accompanying such study, the effect of expanding the base of knowledge within the discipline and the effectiveness of applying this knowledge to immediate problems in so- ciety needs to be examined. The specific ele- ments of such study must include a longitu- dinal examination of the career tracks of criminal justice faculty and students, a cur- riculum analysis for relevance and appropri- ate level of intellectual sophistication, and an organizational examination for commitment to long-term operation. Finally, the increasingly important role of professional associations must be examined. In the absence of traditional faculty activities for research publication, these organizations will continue to serve as alternative channels for disseminating information. Recognition of the role to be played by the smaller, more specialized organizations can only enhance the development of this growing discipline. NOTES 1. Previous studies (Thomas and Bronick, 1984; Travis, 1987) of program quality were specifically con- cerned with doctorate-granting programs in criminal justice studies. We examined only undergraduate pro- grams because the overwhelming majority of beneficia- ries of the L.E.E.P. were undergraduate students. 2. The criteria for quality are established by the au- thors in most studies of academic programs. We al- lowed the respondents to establish the standards of qual- ity for this emerging field. 3. Although many of the program directors had had professional experience, they were academics. Each had earned a Ph.D. (but not necessarily in criminal justice). The raters were clearly qualified to make judgments in regard to program quality. 4. This article reports findings and does not elaborate methodology. The reader needs to remember that this phase of codifying responses is critical and is by no means straightforward. We used the comparative method of Glaser and Strauss (1967). 5. Had we used the preestablished criteria used in most program-rating studies, we would have failed to un- cover some of the dimensions of quality. REFERENCES Chickering, A. W. (1974). Commuting versus resident students: Overcoming educational inequities of living ofS_campus. San Francisco, Jossey-Bass. Garfield, E. (1972). Citation analysis as a tool in jour- nal evaluation. Sci 178: 471-79. Glaser, B., and Strauss, A. (1967). The discovery of grounded theory: Strategies for qualitative research. Chicago: Aldine. Kuykendall, J., and Hemandez, A. (1975). A curricu- lum development model-quality control programming in justice education. Police J 42: 20-22. MaGarrell, L. (1978). Part-time professors on the in- crease. Chron Higher Educ 15: 1. Pearson, R.; Moran, T. K.; Berger, J. C.; Laudon, K. C.; McKenzie, J. R.; and Bonita, T. J. (1967). Crim- inal justice education: The end of the beginning. New York: John Jay Press. Sherman, L. (1978). The quality of police education. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. and McLeod, M. (1979). Faculty characteristics and course content in college programs for police of- ficers. J Crim Just 7: 249-67. Tenney, C. W. (1971). Higher education in programs in law enforcement and criminal justice. Washington, DC: United States Government Printing Office. Thomas, C. W., and Bronick, M. J. (1984). Assessing the quality of doctoral programs in deviance, crimi- nology, and criminal justice. J Crim Just 12: 12-27. Travis, L. W. (1987). Assessing the quality of doctoral programs in deviance, criminology and criminal jus- tice: A response to Thomas and Bronick. J Crim Just 15: 157-64. Ward, R., and Webb, V. (1984). The questfor quality. New York: University Publications. Webster, D. S. (1986). Academic quality ranking of American colleges and universities. Springfield, IL: C. C. Thomas. work_cmyzpjfglndnzc4odxifmpcd64 ---- Seattle Town Meeting Targets Environmental Justice A 554 VOLUME 108 | NUMBER 12 | December 2000 • Environmental Health Perspectives NIEHS News Center Attacks Core Issues in the Land of Apples Seattle, Washington, is an area perhaps best known for high-tech names like Microsoft, Immunex, and Amazon.com. However, much of Washington is rural. The state is a leading producer of tree fruit, berry, and flower crops, which require extensive hand labor—picking and prun- ing—for cultivation and harvest. To meet this demand, Washington’s population of seasonal and full-time farmworkers now numbers about 90,000, according to a report titled Agricultural Work Force in Washington State 1999, published in June 2000 by Washington State Employment Security. Many of these workers and their families are regularly exposed to pesticides, as well as to wood smoke, because wood- stoves are a common source of heat in the rural areas where they live. Researchers at the University of Washington Center for Ecogenetics and Environmental Health (CEEH), located in Seattle, study susceptibility to pesticides, particulate matter in wood smoke, and a wide range of other toxicants from methyl- mercury to solvents to aflatoxins. The CEEH, one of 21 enviromental health sci- ences centers funded by the NIEHS, focuses primarily on the interactions among genet- ics, the environment, and human health. “The development of complex diseases such as many cancers and some chronic degener- ative neurological diseases may never be explained by genetics or environmental exposures alone,” says CEEH director David L. Eaton, a toxicology professor in the Department of Environmental Health and associate dean for research at the School of Public Health and Community Medicine. “CEEH researchers are taking a multidisciplinary approach to study the bio- chemical and molecular mechanisms that influence individual responses to environ- mental risk and exposures.” Approximately 50 CEEH investigators work in many disciplines, including med- ical genetics, epidemiology, toxicology, and pharmaceutical sciences. They are organized into five research cores focused o n h u m a n s y s t e m s . T h e B i o t r a n s - formation Core studies the metabolism of drugs and nondrug chemicals, and the Carcinogenesis Core studies interactions between environmental exposures and g e n e t i c t r a i t s a f f e c t i n g c a n c e r . T h e R e p r o d u c t i v e a n d D e v e l o p m e n t a l Toxicology Core studies the molecular and biochemical mechanisms of reproduc- tive and developmental toxicity, including birth defects, and the Neurotoxicology Core studies mechanisms of neurotoxic damage, including potential environmen- tal factors that may influence the develop- ment of chronic neurologic diseases such as Parkinson and Alzheimer diseases. Finally, the Cardiorespiratory Suscep- tibility Core studies cardiac and respirato- ry function and disease, including asthma and sensitivity to air pollution. The research cores are supported by five facility cores. The Molecular Biomarker Laboratory Core develops gene assays and provides high-throughput genetic analysis. This core is currently developing a new facility that will provide CEEH investiga- tors with access to gene expression array analysis, an addition that will allow investi- gators to study the effects of a variety of exposures or disease conditions on the expression of over 40,000 genes on the human “gene chip” (a glass chip that can be used to screen a single DNA sample for hundreds or thousands of genetic poly- morphisms). Arrays for rat and mouse genomes are also under development. Access to flow cytometry, laser cytome- try–confocal microscopy, and digital i m a g e a n a l y s i s i s p r o v i d e d b y t h e Analytical Cytology Core. The Transgenic Animal Support Core develops transgenic strains and currently maintains about 70 transgenic lines for investigators, and the Molecular Structure Visualization Core provides three-dimensional images of mol- ecules. The fifth core, the Electron Spin Resonance (ESR) Core, uses magnetic res- onance signals to detect and measure the presence of free radicals in tissues. Core Collaborations The CEEH’s organization and the wide variety of services it provides have fostered A center of widespread appeal. Activities at the CEEH run the gamut of science from research studies such as those of Lucio Costa (above, right) and Clement Furlong (above, left) on pesticides, to laboratory training for all levels of students, to outreach programs such as health fairs. Photos: (left, center) Kathy Sauber; (right) Joel Levin numerous collaborations both within the center and with outside facilities. For example, the nearly unique opportunity to work with both ESR and analytical cytol- ogy technology has given a strong boost to CEEH research into the role of the antiox- idant glutathione (GSH) in protecting cells from oxidative stress. This basic research may have wide implications for human health, because free-radical injury is thought to promote aging and contribute to rheumatoid arthritis, many types of can- cers, neurologic disorders such as Alzheimer and Parkinson diseases, and other chronic health problems. Environmental health professors James S. Woods, director of the ESR Core, and Terrance Kavanagh, director of the Analytical Cytology Core, are collaborating on GSH research. They are using ESR technology to measure free-radical produc- tion in intact cells exposed to prooxidant chemicals such as menadione and potassi- um dichromate. Initial results suggest that the ability of a cell to increase GSH pro- duction quickly may be more important than sustained high GSH production in protecting cells against damage caused by free radicals. In future work, Woods and Kavanagh plan to use ESR along with adherent cell analysis and sorting fluores- cent microscopy to determine if transgenic cells and mice that have increased capaci- ties for GSH synthesis are resistant to vari- ous chemicals that generate free radicals. This project has also used the services of the Transgenic Animal Support Core to develop mice that have increased ability to produce GSH, and those of the Molecular Biomarker Laboratory Core to test for the expression of the genes associated with GSH production. Other CEEH researchers have focused on pesticide exposures, specifically varia- tions in the enzyme paraoxonase, which breaks down certain pesticides including diazinon and chlorpyrifos. Lucio Costa, director of the Neurotoxicology Core and a professor of environmental health, and Clement Furlong, a member of the Neurotoxicology Core and a professor of medical genetics, have determined that people can vary in both the amount and type of paraoxonase their bodies produce. As a result, the ability to process common organophosphate insecticides can vary dra- matically among individuals—one adult can have 15 times the paraoxonase blood concentration as another, for instance. Low blood concentrations of paraoxonase, which are linked to less efficient processing of organophosphate pesticides, have also been have been correlated to carotid artery disease. During the first step in chemical oxi- dation of an organophosphate, an inter- mediate oxygenated form of the pesticide, called the oxon form, is created. “We’ve found that the genetic differences in sus- ceptibility bear more on the oxons than on the parent compounds, and that the oxon form is dramatically more toxic than the p a r e n t c o m p o u n d , ” s a y s F u r l o n g . Although the oxon form of a pesticide is generally produced by the body following exposure to the less toxic thioate form of the pesticide, some commercial formula- tions may contain small but significant amounts of the oxon form, and more may be formed following application, accord- i n g t o F u r l o n g . F u r t h e r m o r e , s a y s Environmental Health Perspectives • VOLUME 108 | NUMBER 12 | December 2000 A 555 Furlong, “Safety studies have looked at the parent sulfur compounds almost exclusive- ly, not at the oxons.” Furlong and Costa’s research is using the services of the Transgenic Animal Support Core, which is generating PON1 knockout mice that express isoforms of human PON1, the gene that codes for cre- ation of human paraoxonase. In addition, Elinor Adman and coworkers of the Molecular Structure Visualization Core are in the process of crystallizing paraoxonase to determine its structure. Better informa- tion on the molecule’s structure may allow paraoxonase to be engineered or modified to serve as a therapeutic agent for pesticide poisoning. F u r l o n g h a s d e v e l o p e d a h i g h - throughput assay for determining the type and amount of paraoxonase in blood, which reflects an individual’s susceptibili- ty to the oxon form of specific organo- phosphate pesticides. Currently, Costa a n d F u r l o n g a r e w o r k i n g w i t h o t h e r investigators in the university’s NIEHS- supported Children’s Environmental Health Research Center to study pesticide exposures in children, especially children of farmworkers. This project was based in part on the work of investigators in the R e p r o d u c t i v e a n d D e v e l o p m e n t a l Toxicology Core, which examines critical issues of age- and sex-related susceptibility that are often overlooked, says core direc- tor and environmental health professor Elaine Faustman, who also heads the chil- dren’s health center. The CEEH has also nurtured the development of another major research center, the U.S. Environmental Protection Agency (EPA) Northwest Center for Particulate Air Pollution and Health, which is devoted to detailing exposures, health effects, dosimetry, biomarkers, and mechanisms of particulate matter, especial- ly that found in wood smoke. This center grew out of the work of the Cardio - respiratory Susceptibility Core and is head- ed by core director Jane Koenig, an envi- ronmental health professor. Koenig and colleagues recently found significant associ- ations between amounts of fine particulate matter in the air and emergency room vis- its for asthma by Seattle children eattle [see EHP 107:489–493 (1999)]. They also found that some types of gaseous pollu- tants, such as carbon monoxide, and par- ticulate matter of various diameters corre- lated with increased cardiovascular mortali- ty in Phoenix, Arizona [see EHP 108:347–353 (2000)]. The CEEH is also seeding future work through its successful Pilot Project Program. A total of 24 pilot projects were funded during 1995–2000, the period of the first five-year CEEH grant. Results from 10 of the first 20 of these projects provided the basis for major grants totaling over $5.5 million. In addition, 11 journal articles and 12 abstracts have been pub- lished based on results from these pilot projects. Addressing Ethical, Legal, and Social Issues The CEEH is not only fostering basic research into gene–environment interac- tions but is also looking ahead to under- stand the potential ramifications of this research. This year the CEEH added a new Ethical, Legal, and Social Issues ( E L S I ) C o r e . T h e E L S I C o r e , w h i c h includes investigators from the Schools of Law, Medicine, and Public Health and Community Medicine, identifies and studies ethical, legal, and social implica- tions of scientific advances in the study of gene–environment interactions (“ecoge- netics”) and environmental genomics, or the study of how environmental factors affect the overall expression of genes in human tissues. The ELSI Core is especial- ly interested in how these issues affect genetic variations that are common and have a low probability of causing disease alone, but that may increase disease risk when combined with certain environmen- tal exposures. The focus of the core’s initial case study is on pesticide poisoning susceptibili- ty. “We want these case studies to be sci- ence-based, which is why we’re starting with a gene–environment interaction, where much of the science has already been done and where there is significant potential for ethical and legal ramifica- tions,” says Wylie Burke, ELSI Core deputy director and chairman of the Department of Medical History and Ethics. For example, once tests are com- mercially available to determine paraox- onase status and susceptibility to the effects of certain pesticides, extermination compa- nies might consider the use of such tests in their hiring. “Even though that makes logi- cal sense and seems like a way to protect people who are susceptible to certain chemicals, testing is also a way to label people and to deny them vocational oppor- tunities,” says Burke. Susceptibility research may also have implications for product testing and development. “Should persons with sensitive genotypes be used to set safe or minimum standards for expo- sure?” asks Burke. The ELSI Core also works closely with a public health genetics academic program sponsored by the Department of Epidemiology in the School of Public Health and Community Medicine. This program, developed by ELSI Core director Melissa Austin, trains university graduate students in the study of human genetics in the context of public health. Community Outreach and Education Program In addition to studying the future ramifi- cations of its research, the CEEH is also committed to helping the public make g o o d e n v i r o n m e n t a l h e a l t h c h o i c e s t h r o u g h t h e w o r k o f i t s C o m m u n i t y O u t r e a c h a n d E d u c a t i o n P r o g r a m (COEP). The program’s wide range of activities is illustrated by some of the arti- facts found in its offices. These include artwork created by students living near Chornobyl and brought to the CEEH by visiting Russian teachers, plaster fish used to indicate seafood type and portion size during interviews of non-English-speak- ing Asian–Pacific Islander communities, and a mercury exposure board game cre- ated by school students, the result of a curriculum developed during teacher training workshops. In its first years, the COEP published a 1999 study of seafood consumption and potential health effects from seafood conta- mination among Asian–Pacific Islanders through the EPA, piloted an Environ- mental Risk Information Service hotline, and partnered with the American Lung Association’s Master Home Environ- mentalist Program, which trains volunteers to help local residents reduce the risk of indoor air pollutants in their homes. The COEP recently joined forces with an existing NIEHS K–12 program titled Health and Environmental Resources for Educators at the University of Washington (HERE@UW). HERE@UW brings to the partnership a variety of curricula, exper- tise in conducting teacher workshops, and Tox-in-a-Box, an outreach kit in a brief- case that gives environmental health pro- fessionals the training and props they need to make successful K–12 classroom presentations. In addition to K–12 outreach, the COEP was actively involved in planning a 29–30 September 2000 town meeting, “ V o i c e s f o r H e a l t h y E n v i r o n m e n t s , Healthy Communities,” hosted by the CEEH [see sidebar, next page]. “The planning process for the meeting has given COEP staff an opportunity to con- nect with a wide range of community- based organizations,” says HERE@UW m a n a g e r J o n S h a r p e . “ F u t u r e C O E P opportunities will no doubt grow out of these new relationships.” –Kris Freeman A 556 VOLUME 108 | NUMBER 12 | December 2000 • Environmental Health Perspectives NIEHS News Environmental Health Perspectives • VOLUME 108 | NUMBER 12 | December 2000 A 557 NIEHS News Environmental justice was a key theme of community tes- timony at an NIEHS town meeting titled “Voices for Healthy Environments, Healthy Communities,” held 29–30 September 2000 in Seattle, Washington. Other major themes included concerns about the health effects of pes- ticide exposures (especially among farmworkers), ground- water contamination from radioactive waste at the Hanford Nuclear Site, and a desire for environmental health researchers to be advocates for disease prevention, not just providers of scientific data. More than 200 people attended the meeting, which was cospon- sored by NIEHS and the University of Washington Center for Eco- genetics and Environmental Health along with several community groups and the regional office of the U.S. Environmental Protection Agency. The NIEHS has held a series of town meetings throughout the country during the past four years in order to solicit public input in setting its research agenda. The meetings also provide a forum in which the American public can speak directly with NIEHS director Kenneth Olden and senior NIEHS staff to express their concerns and local experiences with environ- mental health problems. The morning before the meet- ing opened, Olden and other NIEHS representatives visited Seattle’s South Park neighbor- hood, which has a high percent- age of low-income and minority residents, and high loads of air, noise, and chemical pollution from freeways, airports, and industry. U.S. Congressman Jim McDermott (D–Washington) and Washington State Representative Velma Veloria accompanied NIEHS officials on the tour. The town meeting opened Friday evening with a welcoming ceremony that included dancing and com- ments from members of the Suquamish Tribe, and pre- sentations by more than 20 community groups, tribal nations, and youth groups. Saturday morning began with addresses from Olden and Washington State Senator Rosa Franklin, a retired nurse, who spoke on environmental justice. Said Franklin, “A growing body of evidence continues to show that low-income people—a disproportionate percentage of whom are people of color—are more exposed to environmental pollutants than the general population.” The theme of environmental justice continued during Saturday’s open microphone session, which included Latino farmworkers who testified about the effects of pesticide exposures. “Every time a worker moves a piece of fruit or a leaf, they get exposed to pesticides. They get overexposed,” said Guillermo “Bill” Nicacio, a family ser- vice worker with the Washington State Migrant Council. “During apple-thinning season we can tell who is thin- ning because of the redness of their eyes and the rashes on their hands.” During his keynote address, Lupe Gamboa, Washington State regional director of the United Farm Workers of America, AFL-CIO, said, “Farmworkers are treated this way because they don’t have political power and they don’t have economic power.” Gamboa also expressed concern about the lack of training for health care workers in detecting pesticide- induced injury and illness. Throughout the meeting, par- ticipants pressed for more com- munity involvement in research projects, and for researchers to help tackle the environmental health problems that communi- ties identify. “We do need research, but we also need action once we get the information. We need researchers to work with the communities to find solutions to the problems as well,” said Yalonda Sindé, executive director of the Seattle-based Community Coalition for Environmental Justice. Carol Dansereau, execu- tive director of the Washington Toxics Coalition, added that researchers should speak out about the limitations of scientific studies to predict exactly where pollutants will end up and how they will affect different populations. “We want to see decisions based not on risk assessment but on prevention,” she said. Saturday afternoon workshops were led by com- munity and labor leaders, center researchers, and rep- resentatives of local and federal agencies and indus- try. Congressman McDermott chaired a session titled “Air Pollution (Indoor and Outdoor) and Asthma.” Other workshop topics addressed chemical health risks to agricultural workers and their families and environ- mental justice issues. A series of smaller groups dis- cussed topics including water quality, contamination of seafood by marine toxins and pollution, toxic waste, children’s environmental health, and drinking water quality. Further information on the town meeting is avail- able at the “Voices for Healthy Environments, Healthy Communities” Web site at http://depts.washington. edu/townmeet/. –Kris Freeman Focused on the problem. Attendees at the NIEHS town meeting in Seattle consider information and opin- ions on the disparate effects of environmental pollutants on different populations. Kr is Fr ee m an Seattle Town Meeting Targets Environmental Justice work_cr24kcstwnd3boyos3rn2qy5um ---- Of rocks and social justice NATURE GEOSCIENCE | VOL 9 | NOVEMBER 2016 | www.nature.com/naturegeoscience 797 editorial One only has to play a game of ‘spot the geologist’ in San Francisco during the American Geophysical Union meeting to notice that many geoscientists are cut from the same fleece. Indeed, one thing that attracts students to studying geoscience is its culture, where they can establish camaraderie with people of similar inclinations that share interests such as outdoors activities1. In other words, many geoscientists choose the field because they fit in. The consequence of this self-selection is a club of likeminded people. Although membership to this club is not exclusive in principle, in practice it can feel that way to those who do not fit the mould. If geoscience departments truly want to increase diversity — whether this refers to gender, race, ethnicity or anything else — the focus needs to be on cultivating a more welcoming academic culture in which a diverse chorus of voices is valued. Geoscience is one of the least diverse fields of science at Western institutions. In the US, only about 7% of geoscience degrees at both undergraduate and graduate levels are awarded to underrepresented minorities1. The representation of women at degree level is better — they receive in excess of 40% of degrees1,2 — although the representation of women of colour remains appalling. The proportion of women drops off rapidly higher up the career chain3. This so called leaky pipeline has been attributed to many factors, but evidence from letters of recommendation for postdoctoral positions suggests that women are disadvantaged due to their gender from the beginning of their geoscience careers (Dutt, K. et al. 9, 805–808; 2016), most likely not by intention, but by unconscious bias. Those who fit the mould are seen as contributing more to their field than those who do not. There is no shortage of diversity programmes, initiatives and dedicated university administrators claiming to be championing diversity. But if these programmes are working, change has been decidedly slow. It has been shown that diversity programmes implemented by US corporations have not only failed to increase the representation of women and minorities in management roles, but some of these efforts have made the inequality even worse4. Funding diversity programmes allows companies and universities to say they are doing something to fix the problem, but better strategies that deliver actual progress are needed. Two main challenges stand in the way of achieving a diverse geoscience workforce representative of society: we need to attract more people who have not been wearing checkered shirts, walking boots and rucksacks since secondary school, and we need to retain them. On the first point, geoscience departments should branch out. Computer scientists, lab biologists, theoretical physicists and chemists can all contribute key insights to understanding the Earth. And with an increasing focus on sustainable development, it is absolutely essential that all regions of the world and all parts of society are working together. Children today learn relatively little about the geosciences before university, compared to the other branches of science. As a result, outdoors enthusiasm, positive undergraduate experiences and family support account for 80% of active geoscientists5. Conversely, for those to whom these factors do not apply, these doors into the field remain closed. Highlighting the diverse career opportunities and societal relevance of the geosciences could help to attract a broader range of students — after all, not all geoscience careers involve climbing mountains, rock hammer in hand. And then there is the problem of retention. Students from minorities can face systematic exclusion as they carve out careers. The prevalence of harassment — gender-based, race-based, or otherwise — in the academic workplace6 tells us that many geoscience departments are a long way from being inviting environments. Geoscience departments need to ensure that all of their members feel welcome, included, supported and appreciated. These cultural shortcomings are not easy to address, but deserve our energy. Mentoring programs can help, as can fostering support networks7,8. Even if we manage to make our academic environments more diverse, that does not mean that they are also inclusive. If we want to maintain any gains in diversity, we must create environments in which all geoscientists (regardless of colour, gender or inclination to climb a mountain) can flourish. Only then can we hope to stamp out discrimination and bias in the workplace. We owe it to our present and future colleagues to embrace all manner of people into the geosciences, just as we need diversity to tackle the hardest problems. To negotiate the tightening space within the planetary boundaries, two key prerequisits are a workforce that is representative of the world we live in, and as diverse a set of minds as we can get. ❐ References 1. Stokes, P. J., Levine, R. & Flessa, K. W. J. Geosci. Edu. 63, 250–263 (2015). 2. Huntoon, J. E. & Lane, M. J. J. Geosci. Edu. 55, 447–457 (2007). 3. Holmes, M. A., O’Connell, S. & Ongley, L. Nat. Geosci. 1, 79–82 (2008). 4. Dobin, F. & Kalev, A. Why diversity programs fail. Harvard Business Review (July 2016); http://go.nature.com/2egFwUt 5. O’Connell, S. & Holmes, M. A. GSA Today 21, 52–54 (2011). 6. Marín-Spiotta, E., Schneider, B. & Holmes, M. A. Eos http://doi.org/brxq (2016). 7. Huntoon, J. E., Tanenbaum, C. & Hodges, J. Eos http://doi.org/brxr (2015). 8. Sokol, J. Why the universe needs more black and latino astronomers. Smithsonian (23 August 2016); http://go.nature.com/2eg4iAA Despite much emphasis on diversity in the US, geoscience remains one of the least diverse scientific disciplines. If we want to achieve and maintain diversity, we need to make our work environments welcoming to a broad spectrum of voices. Of rocks and social justice Z O O N A R G M BH / A LA M Y S TO C K P H O TO © 2016 Macmillan Publishers Limited, part of Springer Nature. All rights reserved. http://go.nature.com/2egFwUt http://doi.org/brxq http://doi.org/brxr http://go.nature.com/2eg4iAA Of rocks and social justice References work_crf4zzbmqncinncqgd65hyi2ly ---- Family Matters 2011 No. 88 | 5 The wellbeing of Australian families is affected by the resources they have available at present and anticipate will be available in the future (Saunders & Zhu, 2009). Part of that anticipation consists of expectations about what may be left to them by their parents. Those expectations matter. They make a difference to economic planning and to family harmony. They provide young generations with additional assets. They often bring out strong family feelings. In particular, expectations about appropriate and inappropriate inheritance arrangements can lead to misunderstanding, conflict and disharmony in the family. People’s expectations are important also to researchers of family relations and values and to professionals who help people deal with their inheritance arrangements. Lawyers, counsellors, public trustees, for instance, all are involved in helping people make appropriate decisions about bequests. The courts often become the final destination of conflicts that tear families apart, sometimes for several generations. Attracting widespread interest, then, is a current debate about whether there has been a change in what parents are likely to leave, and in parents’ attitudes towards making bequests. One side of the debate proposes that the current older generation of potential inheritance givers can be seen mostly as “Hedonistic Self- Servers”. The other side proposes they can be seen mostly as “Sensible Squirrels”. It would be attractive to be able to take a one- sided perspective on elders as inheritance- givers. It is attractive to think about carefree grey nomads choosing between adventures while fending off decline. That softens the thought of the older generation as self-serving spenders. It also would be attractive to think about grey-headed fairy godmothers and godfathers dispensing gifts to their heirs. That softens the thought of the cautious, perhaps insecure saver. Neither of these perspectives fully covers the phenomena. We take up this debate. First, we lay out several lines of argument in support of the two conflicting perspectives. Then we Jeanette A. Lawrence and Jacqueline J. Goodnow Perspectives on intergenerational bequests Inheritance arrangements and family resources 6 | Australian Institute of Family Studies propose several reservations about taking one perspective or the other, point to a significant gap in the available evidence, and suggest some research that would move the debate beyond one-sided perspectives. For both parts, we draw on some of our own research, particularly a bank of over 200 inheritance narratives given to us by adults across a range of ages (Goodnow & Lawrence, 2008b; 2010; in press). We draw also on other studies, often in other disciplines. Competing perspectives on inheritance giving The debate comes down to the question of whether, in relation to inheritance arrangements, older people are currently thinking and acting more like Hedonistic Self-Servers or Sensible Squirrels. Each of these opposing perspectives focuses on what the older generation do with their financial resources in their old age. The focus is on how much they concentrate on spending their resources on their own pleasure, or on saving their resources for the contingencies of their old age and for having something to leave to their heirs. Perspective 1: The older generation as Hedonistic Self-Servers Identifying Hedonistic Self-Servers The Hedonistic Self-Servers perspective appears in the popular media, in the advertising world, and among some researchers. The argument goes along the lines of “You need to think about yourself more”. The popular term associated with this view of inheritance giving is “The SKIer” (an elder who is “spending the kids’ inheritance”; Rowlingson & McKay, 2006, p. 29). One Australian research group has taken up this side of the debate. Olsberg and Winter (2005) were investigating housing arrangements for the elderly. From their data, they concluded: The attitudes of many men and women towards inheritance has shifted as to what previously would have been considered “the right thing to do” in terms of traditional obligations and responsibilities to their children. Our data strongly suggest that many older people’s attitudes have taken on more of those of their Baby Boomer children; that is “put yourself first”. The desire to bequeath assets to the next generation seems to be significantly diminishing. (p. xii) This claim of a shift among elders towards the hedonistic values ascribed to Baby Boomers amounts to proposing an escalating cross- generational conflict between “your needs and interests—and mine”. At issue, then, is whether there has been a change over time in how elders use their resources—whether there has been a change in what they use for themselves compared with what they leave for their children. At issue also is whether present patterns of behaviour among inheritance-givers affect family resources and family harmony. Supporting the Hedonistic Self-Server perspective Five lines of argument have been offered as supporting the Hedonistic Self-Server perspective: (a) there is a concentration of wealth in older generations; (b) there is evidence of a drop in the amounts that older people are leaving; (c) there are strong advocates of later-life spending on oneself; (d) life in the 21st century is in “a world at risk”; and (e) progression through the life course brings changing demands and challenges. There is a concentration of wealth in older generations This raises questions about giving and keeping. Most older family members now have financial resources and assets that are potentially available for transfer to later generations. According to an Australian Bureau of Statistics (2010) report, the net worth of the average household in 2005–06 peaked at around $824,000 for the 55–64 age group and then decreased to around $575,000 for those in the over 75 age group. Although the average funds decreased with increasing age, there still was disposable wealth. This trend for older people to have a large share of the “wealth pie” has been consistent in Australia and other countries (Kelly & Harding, 2006; Productivity Commission, 2011). In effect, there is no shortage of money that could be left. There is evidence of a drop in the amounts that older people are leaving This trend has been observed in several countries. It especially raises the question of what older people are doing with their comparative wealth, and whether what could be left is being left, or is being spent. There is a distinct possibility that older people are spending money on themselves that they might otherwise have left to their children (e.g., Finch & Mason, 2000, for England; Kelly & Harding, 2006, for Australia). Another possibility is that older people, by dint of living longer, may be spending the money on medical and care expenses for the extra years. We probably need to distinguish between their discretionary The debate comes down to whether, in relation to inheritance arrangements, older people are currently thinking and acting more like Hedonistic Self-Servers or Sensible Squirrels. Family Matters 2011 No. 88 | 7 and non-discretionary spending, but in either case it adds up to having less to pass on. There are strong advocates of later-life spending on oneself The decision of whether or not to pamper oneself in later life is not made in a vacuum. Advocates of spending speak with several voices. Some groups are aggressively urging the older generation to spend their resources. For example, the website of SKI Club Australia (2008) has the motto, “You can’t take it with you. And the kids are all set up in their own career, so our motto is: ‘Help them out as best you can while you’re still around, then spoil yourself’”. Advertising targeting the elder dollar echoes this sentiment; it specifically advises older people on how to spend SKI money on cruises or tours (e.g., “DriveWA on the kids dime”, DriveWA, 2011). Life in the 21st century is in “a world at risk” A sense of risk promotes in people a firm distrust of institutions and an inclination to look after their own interests. Beck (Beck, 2009; Beck & Beck-Gernsheim, 2002) argued that life in this late modern era makes people more conscious of the need to take care of themselves. Social institutions, for instance, insist on dealing with people as individuals rather than as members of functioning family networks. Yet it is the “convoy” of family members working together that Antonucci and Jackson (2007, p. 680) saw as being so effective for giving family members a protective base. In contrast, isolated, individualised responses to institutional demands are well suited as reactions to recent financial crises, especially in the wake of collapsing banks and insurance companies. People who are self-funding their retirement are particularly vulnerable to global financial collapses and to the level of government provisions open to them. As a result, people turn in on their own resources. Elders, according to Beck and Beck-Gernsheim (2002) “can no longer think of themselves only as an ‘appendage’ to the family, but must increasingly see themselves as individuals with their own interests and rights, plans and options” (p. 131). Progression through the life course brings changing demands and challenges Increased attention to oneself is compatible with accounts of what occurs as people move through different periods of life. One major account of life course changes (Havighurst, 1967) points to the changing developmental tasks that occupy people’s attention and energies over time. As people approach older age, it is entirely reasonable for them to take greater interest in what they will do with their money. Part of that is attending to how they will fund their own needs as they age. Another part, according to the advocates of SKIing, also involves attending more to their comfort and adventures. Evidence that age makes a difference in attitudes to inheritance comes from an English study by Rowlingson and McKay (2006). They asked over 2,000 English respondents how much they agreed with statements such as “people should save in order to leave an inheritance”. Agreement turned out to be highest among those respondents below 30 and above 80 in age. It was lowest among those in the 50–59 age group. This group was most likely to be facing the costs of aging, and estimating their options before and after retirement. We also found differences in the specific inheritance norms expressed by younger and older adults, but of a different kind (Goodnow & Lawrence, 2008b). Although each age group displayed a mix of norms for judging inheritance arrangements, an older group with a mean age of 75 years (SD = 8.66) were more likely to be members of cluster groups identified by their endorsement of norms related to individual rights and family feelings. Members of a younger group with a mean age of 18.5 years (SD = 1.02), in contrast, were more likely to be in a cluster endorsing norms People who are self-funding their retirement are particularly vulnerable to global financial collapses and to the level of government provisions open to them. 8 | Australian Institute of Family Studies related to family heritage. We now need data on how these competing individual rights and family heritage norms are being expressed in patterns of spending and keeping. Perspective 2: The older generation as Sensible Squirrels Identifying Sensible Squirrels There is an alternative perspective. It involves seeing the older generation not primarily as SKIers, but as squirrels—squirrels saving their resources for rainy days. Those rainy days would be either in their own future or the future of their children. The current emphasis, however, is on saving and then using the money as needed for the demands and problems that they are experiencing or anticipating in their own future. This motif resonates with the experiences of older generations who lived through the Great Depression and the aftermath of World War II. Its iconic imagery is the box under the bed, along with a firm determination to have “at least enough to bury me decently” (as commented by one of the study participants; Goodnow & Lawrence, in press). Supporting the Sensible Squirrel perspective There are at least five lines of argument that counter the hedonistic perspective, which point to contemporary elders as being concerned bequesters, or at least as Saving Squirrels whose activities mean some resources are left for their children: (a) the concentration of wealth in older generations could give rise to a variety of patterns of giving; (b) there is evidence of parents’ commitments to making bequests to their children; (c) in a world of risk, bequests may be accidental instead of intended; (d) there is a distinction between during-life and end-of- life giving; and (e) progression through the life course involves striking a balance. The concentration of wealth in older generations could give rise to a variety of patterns of giving That concentration does not mean that elders will automatically spend their wealth on themselves. The average figures of concentrated wealth also can mask the variability in expendable finances in the older generation (Productivity Commission, 2011, p. 59). Older parents may have more than they had imagined to either leave or to use. This can be the outcome of tax laws, frugal living, careful saving, or, in some cases, an explosion in the value of the family home. Bequests have not entirely suffered in older people’s planning. They are common practice and often sizable. In one US study (Dynan, Sinner, & Zeldes, 2002), the size of bequests was up to six times the average earnings of an older group of elders. Although placing considerable value on leaving bequests, this group did not say they were saving specifically in order to make those bequests. According to Dynan et al., that kind of specification would have just meant adding another motive on top of their already careful and precautionary saving. There is evidence of parents’ commitments to making bequests to their children The wish to have something to leave the children transcends cultural and legal contexts. Although people may have a variety of reasons for making bequests, there seems to be a general perspective that one will leave some family legacy (Rowlingson & McKay, 2006). While inheritance gifts are more concentrated in the wealthy, that concentration is not exclusive to those with much to leave. The desire to leave something, however, may not sit lightly with a growing social expectation that older people should be prepared to contribute more to their own care needs. That expectation comes into collision with people’s desire to leave intact one particular source of potential wealth—the family home. Although people may have a variety of reasons for making bequests, there seems to be a general perspective that one will leave some family legacy. Family Matters 2011 No. 88 | 9 A recent draft report by the Productivity Commission (2011), for instance, proposed that older people should be expected to make contributions to their care. The Commission noted that over 83% of people of 65 and over own or are buying their own home. It proposed that a government-backed equity release scheme would allow these people to borrow against the equity in their homes with no (or limited) repayments until the home is transferred to another person. The journalist Ross Gittins (2011) vigorously took up this proposal, challenging people to discuss with him online the appropriateness of hanging onto the home as an intact resource. He argued that with the escalating cost of care, elders and their inheritance-conscious children can no longer reserve assets for passing on to younger generations. That argument is not popular. In our bank of narratives, one father who needed to move to assisted accommodation, for example, engaged in a running battle with his children about the quality and cost of different care facilities. He did not want to spend. They wanted him to spend. In the end, the children could not persuade him to sell the family home and go to the better facility. He preferred to keep the asset of the home intact for his heirs rather than to buy extra comfort and services for himself. In a world of risk, bequests may be accidental instead of intended Funds in excess of need may be accrued as people focus on making sure they have enough for their needs (Pestieau, 2003). Many people squirrel away their assets, hoping they will have enough to last them out. As a result, unforeseen death leaves some heirs with unexpectedly generous amounts. Their parents’ resources outlast their needs, with their frugal living and saving resulting in the generous proportions of these accidental bequests. One financial advisor told us about an older couple who had been particularly frugal in their spending during their early retirement. They wanted to make sure they had enough for when they were older. Now in their older years, they regretted not spending more when they were fitter. They had had more than enough to do so. According to Dynan et al. (2002): Wealth is something like traveller’s checks: you take them along on vacation “just in case”, but the odds are they will remain uncashed and available for sundry goods after the journey is complete. (p. 724) There is a distinction between during-life and end-of-life giving Analyses of parents’ transfers of resources need to include more than the will and other end-of-life provisions. One-sided support for the hedonistic perspective loses some of its power when other forms of transfer between generations are counted alongside bequests. Parents may have already given substantial amounts to their children during their lifetimes. Early, carefully intended transfers can be a reasonable response to legal regulations. In the US, for example, state taxes are likely to be levied on what is left at the time of a parent’s death. Consequently, many parents work out intricate ways of providing for their children over the years to avoid death taxes (Pestieau, 2003). In Australia, which has no death taxes, there are other restrictions on patterns of transfer (e.g., gift taxes). In Islamic countries, some distinct advantages are attached to giving assets away before death. It is possible, for example, to give money to one’s children, kin or foundations in ways that will leave little to be covered by the Koranic distribution codes that normally apply (Carroll, 2001). In general, there appears to be considerable variability in how people give resources to their children while they are alive compared with bequests. McGarry (1999), for example, found that transfers made during the parents’ lifetimes are more likely to benefit less well-off children. Inheritance bequests, however, are generally more likely to be equally divided between children. Similarly, unequal giving prompted by reciprocity seemed to be more acceptable among Japanese adult children while a parent was still alive, but less acceptable in inheritance situations (Izuhara, 2004). Progression through the life course involves striking a balance Regardless of historical changes, Erikson’s (1968) classic theory of psychosocial development continues to provide insights into the ways in which people balance competing demands. For all phases of the life course, it portrays the need for people to find their way through normative crises. These crises pull them in different ways that can lead to positive or negative resolutions of the crises (e.g., being over-self-protective or over-generous). Striking a balance between tendencies to be cautious or to be generous is another way of viewing the choices available to the wealthy generation. With the trend for people to live longer and more actively, the Eriksonian crisis that demands a balance between There appears to be considerable variability in how people give resources to their children while they are alive compared with bequests. 10 | Australian Institute of Family Studies “generativity and stagnation” probably is now more applicable to people of older ages. It is relevant to how older people see and use their resources. Their balancing act, set within broad social trends, is not only important for their children’s wellbeing, but for their own. Striking this balance is a prelude to handling Erikson’s next crisis of “integrity versus despair”, as they face the end of their lives. The timing of Erikson’s age-related crises has changed as people live longer and take longer to traverse early adulthood. People in early old age are therefore often still balancing demands made upon them by the next generation with the demands of their own living. Reservations and future directions for research We may ask if it matters which of the perspectives discussed here dominates the discussion of inheritance arrangements and future lines of research. Is there a possibility of resolving the debate on one side or the other? Our answer to these two questions is, “Yes, it matters, but no, a resolution that favours only one side is not feasible”. The direction now needed, we suggest, is one of specifying reservations to one-sided solutions, and the research that would help fill the gaps that these reservations highlight. Our reservations are of several kinds. They start with the need for attention to diversity: diversity in parents’ motives, forms of wealth, the way in which wealth is distributed, the way in which bequests are communicated, and the nature of the match between the views of generations. Still to receive close attention is a particular gap that has to do with the interplay between norms that pull in different directions, and with the circumstances that help shape the norms that people hold about what is feasible and what should happen. Parents’ motivations for making bequests can take several forms It is unlikely that parents’ motivations can be reduced solely to the two perspectives of hedonism or careful squirreling for rainy days or late-life demands. What is needed then is to specify other diverse forms that motivations may take. One move in this direction is the proposal that even if we cut motivations down to two forms (in this case, altruism and exchange), the critical issue will be the relative strengths of these two (e.g., see McGarry, 1999). An alternative direction involves exploring parents’ motives in ways that allow diversity to come to the surface. An example is a study by Sousa, Silva, Santos and Paträo (2010). They analysed people’s stories of critical incidents related Family Matters 2011 No. 88 | 11 to inheritance in Portugal. There, distributing equal shares to one’s children is the law, and people have freedom to bequeath only a third of their assets as they choose. Nonetheless, Sousa and her colleagues discovered eight patterns of motivation. As well as equality, these included motives of altruism, exchange and egoism, and these motives were not completely at odds. Instead, they could be laid on a continuum defined by the endpoints of altruism and egoism, with equality and exchange as interim points. Along similar lines is the proposal that inheritance arrangements reflect the relative strengths of seeing them as predominantly serving instrumental or expressive functions. Parents’ support for their children, for example, can be instrumental (e.g., covering the costs of children becoming less dependent), expressive (e.g., specific gifts with loving symbolism that matches the gift carefully to the receiver), or a mix of the two (Nauck, 2010). Bequests exclusively involving money also can take expressive as well as instrumental forms of giving. The expression is often conveyed in an accompanying message (e.g., “This amount is for X’s special trip”). Several of our narrators, for example, told of inheritance arrangements where the older giver went to great lengths to say that certain gifts of money were expressing love and concern (e.g., fulfilling a child or grandchild’s dream of travel, giving them a car, or funding a special course of study; Goodnow & Lawrence, 2008a). In some cases, the specific sum of money may convey to the receiver that the money is for a special project that they had talked about previously within a loving relationship. Wealth can take several forms Wealth can take the form of cash, shares, bonds, interest-bearing deposits or superannuation funds. All these can be converted into cash in hand, ready for distribution. The older generation’s resources, however, may be tied up in a house, other property or a family business. These resources are not readily converted into funds that can be used or that can be distributed among several potential heirs. Money is divisible, houses are not. People may be willing to use cash in hand either for necessities or for pleasure, but they are less likely to plunder the family home. We now need analyses of how what is left or what is kept aside for other purposes varies with the main sources of parents’ wealth. The explosion in house prices, for instance, may well alter the sources of wealth. An ordinary suburban home may yield a generous estate, and the legacy of the house may then be large enough to affect the fortunes of the next generation. That effect may be positive (e.g., in the amount left) or negative (e.g., in the potential for family conflict over what is left). The proposals from the Productivity Commission (2011) and Gittins (2011) certainly make it clear that suggestions of turning the equity of the family home into useable funds can touch on sensitive family matters. Distributions can take varied forms A general starting point for wealth distribution seems to be to “treat the children equally”. Although that starting point may be honoured more in intent than in practice, any actual departures from equality seem to require explanation. We now need to pay closer attention to the nature of those justifications and to the circumstances that can give rise to departures from equal distributions to children. Drake and Lawrence (2000), for example, asked an older group of adults (aged between 63 and 91 years) how they would allocate a set amount of money between children who varied in gender, need, and merit (i.e., providing support for parents). Departures from equal distributions of money did not occur when the difference was only on the basis of gender, but they were more frequent on the basis of differences in need than merit. Need exerted the stronger pull. Still stronger were combinations of need and merit. Light and McGarry (2004) add further material. From within a sample of 5,000 mothers aged 45–80, they drew out 1,490 who had already made wills. Most of these mothers started with the intention of leaving equal shares. When they did make unequal bequests, those departures from equality were related either to the mother’s own poor health (probably giving more to children who provided care), their predictions of variations in their children’s income levels or, in the case of blended families, the biological status of their children (giving more to natural than adopted children). There is still much to learn about how elders perceive the personal circumstances of different family members as grounds for departures from strict equality. As one step forward, we presented research participants with a series of vignettes that asked for their approval or disapproval of other people’s inheritance arrangements that had caused problems (Goodnow & Lawrence, 2008a). In one of these, a mother leaves to one especially needy daughter more than she Departures from equal distributions of money … were more frequent on the basis of differences in need than merit. Need exerted the stronger pull. 12 | Australian Institute of Family Studies leaves to the others. When asked for their comments on this way of making unequal shares, people in general were sympathetic about the mother’s response to her child’s financial needs. The unequal distribution was acceptable, provided that some other criteria were met. Unequal shares should in no way stem from “favouritism”, “undue influence” or “collusion”. In addition, most participants felt that if there were to be an unequal distribution, the other heirs should be informed, and informed in advance. It should not come as a shock. Bequests on intentions may be communicated and carried out in several ways We have already mentioned one example of communicating intentions about bequests: the significance of telling people in advance that the distribution of shares will be unequal. Heirs, above all, need to know where they stand in planned arrangements. There is little sympathy for secretive readings of wills. While a certain amount of non-disclosure may be self-preserving, it also may leave an unpleasant memorial. The need now is to recognise that styles of communication and interpersonal interactions carry their own weight, over and above how items are distributed. To date, there has been little analysis of how forms of communication affect the acceptance of various inheritance arrangements. Yet to be understood, for example, is whether disinherited family members react like disenfranchised workers. Tyler (2000) has shown that people affected by decisions in occupational and legal settings are able to tolerate unfavourable outcomes if they think the processes of decision-making were procedurally fair. Testing the extent of concerns about communication and other procedures in inheritance situations could link inheritance studies to other areas where people make significant judgements that are tuned to their sense of fairness. Part of communication style also has to do with occasions when family members feel they have been treated unfairly in distributions, and turn to the court. It is time for a closer look at the way in which people present their case to lawyers or to the court, and the kind of advice and judgements they find there. They may well be advised, for example, to emphasise need rather than how well they looked after their parents. Orientations of two generations do not always match When parents and children are of one mind about the use of the parents’ assets, it is not too difficult to make decisions about what to leave and to whom. Consensus can be achieved. The family enters areas of conflict when what the parents expect is not what the children expect. That lack of consensus can even violate the sense of being a family. One of our narrators, for example, ended his story about an inheritance arrangement he felt went wrong with the comment: “And this was supposed to be a family!” We now need evidence of any variability or, alternatively, any consensus among older and younger members of the same families. More revealing will be information about the grounds for similar and different views. When, for instance, is a lack of match likely to occur and to provoke family tension? One kind of occasion, our narratives suggest, is when parents leave their assets to people that some family members do not regard as family. Subsequent wives or husbands, children from subsequent marriages, and stepchildren and adopted children are often seen as not being completely “in the family”, as not being entitled to the same bequests that should apply to “full” family members. A middle-aged man in one of our narratives, for example, asked his father to take a second mortgage on his modest house in order to help him, the son, get a home loan. Indeed, he argued that since his father had a new partner who would have residency rights for some years after the father died, he, the son, was effectively being cut out of his expected inheritance from the sale of the family home. Therefore, he claimed, he was due some extra financial support now; “That house is my inheritance. I am dependent on that when you go”. The father did not agree that his son was entitled to this form of financial support now. He countered that his own lifestyle would be severely cramped if there were a long-term debt hanging over his head. He had already covered what the son was entitled to expect: “I have helped you all your life. Now it is time for me to look after myself in my older years”. Responses to societal changes can vary, and are not all one-sided Responses to social changes such as global risk and financial crises are not exclusive to retirees. Younger people are likely to have more precarious holds on social resources than When parents and children are of one mind about the use of the parents’ assets, it is not too difficult to make decisions about what to leave and to whom. Family Matters 2011 No. 88 | 13 their elders. As Beck & Beck-Gernsheim (2002) pointed out, young people in the 21st century are increasingly obliged to construct their own “do-it-yourself biographies” as they work to establish career and family lives in uncertain circumstances. The uncertainties of contemporary life also mean that adult children have changing perspectives on relationships and responsibilities. Izuhara (2004) reported how a breakdown in traditional generational contracts for elder care in Japan has been accompanied by the expressed wish for more independence by adult children. In a study of inheritance expectations across six cultures, Nauck (2010) recently found further evidence of a general shift towards greater attention to giving personal objects that express relationships rather than material values. What needs to be considered are how relationships and circumstances may influence people’s behaviours and motives. A particular gap: The interplay of norms Up to this point, we have been concerned with reservations, gaps and future directions related to the recognition of greater diversity than the two perspectives of hedonism and squirreling imply. To these we need to add another largely overlooked issue—the interplay of conflicting norms that pull people in different directions. That issue is critical for understanding people’s behaviours and motives. People function on the basis of a variety of concerns or norms about what is the right thing to do in specific situations. These concerns or norms rarely point people to only one way to proceed. Concerns about family harmony and individual rights, for example, are likely to pull elders in different directions when they are trying to resolve different calls on their affections, values and resources. It would be acting out of character, for example, for previously loving and supportive parents to suddenly turn into SKIers once they have more money than they ever imagined. However much they are enticed by trips and cruises, they are not likely to entirely dismiss “our kids’ needs”. Similarly, squirrels may also be torn when they are working out how much to go on saving “just in case”, and how much they can give away. Some of the pull may depend on whose rainy day has now come. One wants to be “a good parent”, but not “a soft touch”. As experienced by the father in the second mortgage narrative, the pull of obligation (to be a provider) may compete with the pull of a sense of fairness—that one has “already done enough” for a particular child. We now need concepts and methods that will advance our understanding of the pull of different norms. That will involve understanding more about how people’s norms and values are influenced by cultural ideologies and legal codes. Even more searching and sorely needed are analyses that deal with how norms, ideologies and legal codes all interact with particular sets of circumstances. We need to know, for instance, the impact on people’s commitments of what they see as appropriate and right when their circumstances alter. Do considerations of what is appropriate and right, for instance, take precedence in the face of one’s own growing frailty, or are they given up or modified in the face of difficult circumstances? Does the pull of family harmony weaken in favour of concerns about individual rights and deservedness? Conclusion The financial wellbeing of a family obviously owes much to how its elders use the resources that are available to them. How these resources are passed on is closely tied to norms and expectations about obligation and entitlement. How the older generation exercises its own entitlement is not only a potential source of conflict within the family. It also remains an open question for family researchers. The pull of obligation (to be a provider) may compete with the pull of a sense of fairness—that one has “already done enough” for a particular child. 14 | Australian Institute of Family Studies Throughout, the evidence has pointed to the significance of achieving a balanced orientation to inheritance arrangements—a balance in approaches to spending and saving, a balance in judgements about the appropriate divisions of assets, a balance between competing norms. We have already pointed to the attraction of taking a one-sided view of how elders make their inheritance arrangements. One-sided views not only fail to take account of the evidence, but they sell short the experiences, demands and norms that pull bequest-makers in different directions. Instead of carefree nomads or benevolent fairy godmothers and godfathers, it may be more useful to think about elders as ageing jugglers. They are juggling their own needs and interests along with the needs and interests of the family. That is a handful in anyone’s terms. References Antonucci, T., & Jackson, J. S. (2007). Intergenerational relations: Theory, research, and policy. Journal of Social Issues, 63, 679–693. Australian Bureau of Statistics. (2010). Measures of Australia’s progress, 2010 (Cat No. 1370.0). Retrieved from . Beck, U. (2009). World at risk. Cambridge: Polity Press. Beck, U., & Beck-Gernsheim, E. (2002). Individual- ization: Institutionalized individualism and its social and political consequences. London: Sage. Carroll, L. (2001). Life interests and intergenerational transfer of property avoiding the law of succession. Islamic Law and Society, 8, 245–286. Dynan, K., Skinner, J., & Zeldes, S. (2002). The importance of bequests and life-cycle saving in capital accumulation: A new answer. American Economic Association: Papers and Proceedings, 92(2), 274–278. Drake, D. G., & Lawrence, J. A. (2000). Equality and distributions of inheritance in families. Social Justice Research, 13, 271–290. DriveWA. (2011). Spend the kids inheritance. Perth: DriveWA. Retrieved from . Erikson, E. (1968). Identity: Youth and crisis. New York: W. W. Norton. Finch, J., & Mason, J. (2000). Passing on: Kinship and inheritance in England. London: Routledge. Gittins, R. (2011, 26 January). Aged care dilemma: Tap wealth in homes, or let taxpayers pay. The Age. Retrieved from . Goodnow, J. J., & Lawrence, J. A. (2008a). How should people act in inheritance situations? Specifying differences in expectations. International Journal of Behavioral Development, 32, 98–107. Goodnow, J. J., & Lawrence, J. A. (2008b). Inheritance events: Perceptions of actions that involve the giving and receiving of things. Forum Qualitative Sozialforschung/Forum Qualitative Social Research, 9(1), Art. 25. Retrieved from . Goodnow, J. J., & Lawrence, J. A. (2010). Inheritance norms for distributions of money, land and things in families. Family Science: Global Perspectives on Research, Policy and Practice, 1(2), 73–82. Goodnow, J. J., & Lawrence, J. A. (in press). Inheriting money, houses, land, things: The way it’s supposed to be in families. Charlotte, NC: Information Age Publishing Inc. Havighurst, R. J. (1967). Developmental tasks and education. New York: David McKay. Izuhara, M. (2004). Negotiating family support? The “generational contract” between long-term care and inheritance. Journal of Social Policy, 33, 694–663. Kelly, S., & Harding, A. (2006). Don’t rely on the old folks’ money: Inheritance patterns in Australia. Elder Law Review, 5, 1–14. Light, A. & McGarry, K. (2004). Why parents play favorites: Explanations for unequal bequests. The American Economic Review, 94(5), 1669–1681. McGarry, K. (1999). Inter vivos transfers and intended bequests. Journal of Public Economics, 73, 321–351. Nauck, B. (2010). Intergenerational relationships and female inheritance expectations: Comparative results from eight societies in Asia, Europe, and North America. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology, 41, 690–705. Pestieau, P. (2003). The role of gift and estate transfers in the United States and in Europe. In A. H. Munnell & A. Sundén (Eds.). Death and dollars: The role of gifts and bequests in America (pp. 64–90). Washington, DC: Brookings Institute Press. Productivity Commission. (2011). Caring for older Australians: Draft inquiry report. Canberra: Commonwealth of Australia. Olsberg, D., & Winters, M. (2005). Ageing in place: Intergenerational and intrafamilial housing transfers and shifts in later life (AHURI Final Report No. 88). Melbourne: Australian Housing and Urban Research Institute. Rowlingson, K., & McKay, S. (2006). Attitudes to inheritance in Britain. Bristol: The Policy Press. Saunders, P., & Zhu, A. (2009). Comparing disadvantage and well-being in Australian families. Australian Journal of Labour Economics, 12(1), 21–39. SKI Club of Australia. (2008). Welcome to SKI Club Australia. Caboolture, QLD: Community Website Developments (Aust) Pty Ltd. Retrieved from . Sousa, L., Silva, A. R., Santos, L., & Paträo, M. (2010). The family inheritance process: Motivations and patterns of interaction. European Journal of Ageing, 7, 5–15. Tyler, T. (2000). Social justice: Outcome and procedure. International Journal of Psychology, 35, 117–125. Jeanette A. Lawrence is at Psychological Sciences, The University of Melbourne. Jacqueline J. Goodnow is at the Institute for Early Childhood, Macquarie University. Correspondence concerning this paper should be sent to: Jeanette A. Lawrence, Psychological Sciences, The University of Melbourne, Melbourne, Victoria, 3010. An earlier version of this paper was presented at the 11th Australian Institute of Family Studies Conference, 9 July 2010. Throughout, the evidence has pointed to the significance of achieving balance—a balance in approaches to spending and saving, a balance in judgements about the appropriate divisions of assets, a balance between competing norms. work_csctkijyd5hhdppzduazvwcdsm ---- ESA and Environmental Justice Howard University From the SelectedWorks of George Middendorf March, 2007 ESA and Environmental Justice George Middendorf, Howard University Charles Nilon Available at: https://works.bepress.com/george-middendorf/9/ http://www.howard.edu https://works.bepress.com/george-middendorf/ https://works.bepress.com/george-middendorf/9/ Contributions Commentary Eco-justicE 160 Bulletin of the Ecological Society of America ESA and Environmental Justice Ecologists’ interest in environmental justice (EJ) issues has spurred increasing consideration about the rela- tionship between EJ and ecology. Over the past several years, ecologists have sponsored symposia, roundtables, and discussions at ESA Annual Meetings. In 2000, speakers included G. Middendorf on ESA’s relationship to environmental justice, N. Targ on EPA’s role in environmental justice, J. Cubit on ecology in court to serve envi- ronmental justice, and C. Hopkins on black is green: a baseline study of environmental programs at historically black colleges and universities. In 2002, G. Middendorf and B. Grant discussed ecology, environmental history, environmental justice, and the role of ecologists in society; C Nilon spoke about the North City Sustainable Communities Project: linking research, restoration, and community involvement, T. Woiwode addressed The GreenWays Initiative: building the community of southeast Michigan; R. Tohannie, T. Alcoze, A. Moote, and S. Oran asked, who speaks for the mycorrhizae? environmental justice in Southwest forest restoration; J. Bonet outlined challenges and rewards of multilingual outreach; M. Floyd and C. Outley talked about children’s perceptions of neighborhood risks: an environmental justice perspective; N. Cole showed how climate change threatens the most vulnerable; and L. Jablonski and T. Poling discussed Environmental Justice and religious movements—restoring engagement in the world. In August 2006, George Middendorf, Charles Nilon, and Leanne Jablonski convened a symposium, Link- ing Ecology and Environmental Justice, in which nine presentations delineated specific links between ecology and EJ. Each speaker was asked to examine links between his or her research, teaching, and life as an ecologist with environmental justice issues, needs, and opportunities. As you will see in the presentations included in this issue of the ESA Bulletin, each has done so in a different manner. While each is, obviously, consistent with the speaker’s own history and interpretation of how these two disciplines might link, the results, although individu- ally unique, reveal that each speaker thought it critical to establish links between ecology and environmental justice—and that the development of strong links was critical to the future of both areas. In this symposium, Steward Pickett, Mary Cadenasso, and Chris Boone discussed “The ecology of environ- mental justice: relationships to ecological theory; John Vandermeer and Ivette Perfecto related “Tropical conser- The following papers were presented at the ESA 2006 Annual Meeting in Memphis, Tennessee, at the Symposium: Linking Ecology and Environmental Justice. Contributions vation and grass roots social movements;” Doug Boucher spoke about “The exploitation of natural resources and the people who extract them”; Hank Howe, in his talk, “Is curiosity good for anybody?,” considered how society and societal values affect ecological research; Ann Bartuska and Lynne Westphal talked about “Restoring justice/ restoring ecosystems: the intersection of ecology and environmental justice.” Marie Miranda, Joe Aldy, and Bill Schlesinger’s discussion of “Resistance and resilience as frameworks for understanding the justice implications of global climate change” is not included in this issue of the ESA Bulletin, as they decided to submit it elsewhere. Kristin Shrader-Frechette addressed the often confusing “and/or” issue of “Saving nonhuman species, killing humans”; and Leanne Jablonski and Para Poling discussed the specific role of ESA in EJ in their talk, “Environ- mental justice and ecology: developing the ESA agenda.” We believe that each of the talks presented in this issue of the ESA Bulletin is interesting, useful, and ulti- mately, transformative. Defining environmental justice and the role of ecology In the early 1980s, EJ activist efforts focused on the disproportionate siting of waste dumps in minority com- munities. Increased recognition of environmental disparities led to the development of EJ from the civil rights movement, with historical antecedents in the social work and feminist movements of the early 20th century. EJ passed through several earlier incarnations: environmental racism and environmental equity. EJ differs from these in that EJ is defined by its recognition that 1) disparate and disproportionate environmental impacts occur among different communities across racial and socio-economic lines, 2) affected communities should be apprised of environmental issues affecting them, and 3) these communities should be incorporated in any decision-making process. Of the three components, the first and third, recognition and inclusion, are probably best addressed through political and social venues, and it was to that end that President Clinton mandated in Executive Order 12898 To the greatest extent practicable and permitted by law, and consistent with the principles set forth in the report on the National Performance Review, each Federal agency shall make achieving environmental justice part of its mission by identifying and addressing, as appropriate, disproportionately high and adverse human health or environmental effects of its programs, policies, and activities on minority populations and low-income populations…. The effectiveness and success of this order remains problematic—and a topic for discussion in another venue. The second component is the one where application of ecology appears most fruitful and critical as this com- ponent concerns the use and role of science—and it is this aspect that was the focus of this symposium. Histori- cally, early EJ efforts centered on health-related issues and their causes, e.g., waste sites, pollutants, and the like. Thus, the relationship of science and EJ has largely centered on assessing differential environmental impacts on communities and developing associated models of risk, costs, and benefits. Science for EJ has been concentrated in sociological, health, and economic studies. What remains to be integrated into this are the natural sciences, particularly ecology. While this seems a reasonably simple and straightforward task, there are several barriers that make it difficult. April 2007 161 Contributions First, historical connections between EJ and ecology are lacking. The largely white ecological community is quite different from the mostly minority EJ community (which, in the United States, includes African American, His- panic American and Native American proponents and practitioners, but also economically disadvantaged white populations like Appalachia). Because ecologists are academically located in the natural sciences and EJ prac- titioners mostly come from the social and health sciences, it has been difficult to cross disciplinary boundaries. The focus differs as well; ecologists examine broad, general processes, while EJ practitioners focus on specific situations. Because of these community, disciplinary, and historical differences, individuals active in ecology and EJ have often (perhaps almost always) not interacted with one another. It is our belief that not only need this not be so, but that each will benefit greatly from the other. Natural science and ecology are critical for assessment of environmental impacts on communities and for developing models to examine the risks, costs, and benefits associated with environmental public policy. On the other hand, EJ is critical in providing focus and support for ecologists and ecological studies. That they are not exclusive is best exemplified by the work of two professors of urban planning. Corburn (2002, 2005) articulates an environmental approach that combines community-based research with local environmental knowledge to deal with asthma and subsistence-fishing hazards. Such an ap- proach could either be combined with ecological studies of nutrient cycles, or used as a basis for future ecologi- cal studies. Spirn’s (2000, 2005) long-term studies of the Mill Creek neighborhood in Philadelphia stand out as an exemplar of the role ecology should play in environmental planning. But just how linked (or unlinked) are Ecology and EJ? A survey of the Web of Science from January to June 2006 using “environmental justice” as keywords revealed 1078 results appearing in 41 publications, only one of which might be considered peripheral by most ecologists, Ecological Economics. A keyword search in Amazon and Barnes and Noble web sites using “environmental justice” for books published between January and July 2006 revealed 22 books, of which only three could be thought ecologically orientated, Burke’s Focus on Ecol- ogy (an edited volume), Gore’s An Inconvenient Truth (to accompany the movie of the same name), and Gleik’s The World’s Water 2006–2007 (a biennial report on freshwater resources). EJ is a research focus of a number of fields, but rarely for traditional ecologists. EJ is seen in anthropology, sociology, chemical, civil, and environ- mental engineering, history, law, library and information science, medicine, nursing, public health, etc, but not ecology. We conclude that there really isn’t much linkage between the two. EJ has been viewed by ecologists, and others (see Foreman 1998, for instance), as either advocacy or as an inappropriate research topic—probably because of its origin as a grassroots environmental movement among communities of color. Several misconceptions and preconceptions have acted toward this end. Reframing ecology—and EJ One misconception has been how we, as scientists, narrowly define and view research. Traditionally, we have framed research as basic, where science is conducted for its own sake or as applied when conducted either for or as the result of policy. Only occasionally do we recognize a hybrid approach in which basic and applied research are combined by extending a basic research framework into the human domain. This last approach is increasingly important in addressing critical scientific issues (those defined by individuals and communities outside the acad- emy), gaining public support for research, and providing information to the public for use in the policy process. Incorporation of EJ into ecology represents an method that would not only increase integration of ecology into the resolution of critical environmental issues, but also create new funding opportunities for ecologists, expand inter- est in the field of ecology among members of underrepresented groups, and involve residents of local communi- 162 Bulletin of the Ecological Society of America https://www.researchgate.net/publication/11435255_Combining_community-based_research_and_local_knowledge_to_confront_asthma_and_subsistence-fishing_hazards_in_GreenpointWilliamsburg_Brooklyn_New_York?el=1_x_8&enrichId=rgreq-a8f3aaf1f24590f82e5fb33605a09e02-XXX&enrichSource=Y292ZXJQYWdlOzI1MDA3ODIzMTtBUzozMjcxNDc5NjYyMjIzMzZAMTQ1NTAwOTU2MTMzOQ== Contributions ties in environmental research and decision making. Each of these fulfills the goals and mission of the ESA. One preconception is that because EJ has relied on sociology and economics, it does not need ecology. This is not unsurprising given the roles of science generally outlined in the EJ literature, which suggests that science is important in: 1) Evaluation of risk, cost, and benefits, usually associated with chemical and toxic exposures within and across communities. The particular exposures or specific issues have not often included ecology as a factor af- fecting exposure level. This is either due to the lack of ecologists doing EJ, or to the fact that ecologists are generally unaware of or insensitive to EJ issues, perhaps because they do not live in affected communities or are uncomfortable in dealing with the communities involved. 2) Evaluation of combined and synergistic exposure impacts within a context of individual communities. Ecologists are not trained for this. 3) Assignment of specific risk levels, costs, and benefits to impacted, potentially impacted, and other com- munities. Ecologists are often unaware of the need for this and certainly are not trained in the sociological, eco- nomic, and health dimensions of such problems. 4) Providing information to affected communities and decision-makers in a reasoned and unbiased manner. If ecologists are not involved in Nos. 1–3, they are most unlikely to be involved with No. 4. Clearly, if ecology is to have a relationship with EJ, ecologists must begin by delineating the very role of ecology in EJ. We believe that an understanding of ecology and ecological principles is critical in understanding and deal- ing with EJ issues. For instance, the top 10 key ecological concepts identified by BES members (Cherrett 1989) were (in rank order): the ecosystem, succession, energy flow, conservation, competition, niche, materials cycling, the community, life history patterns, and ecosystem fragility. Similarly, the ESA web page notes that members conduct research, teach, and use ecological science to address environmental issues that include: biotechnology, ecological restoration, ecosystem management, habitat alteration and destruction, natural resource management, ozone depletion and climate change, species extinction and loss of biological diversity, and sustainable ecologi- cal systems. A quick look at some of these areas will illustrate possible links between ecology and EJ. Biotechnology As food production becomes increasingly split among industrial, organic, and local approaches, the ability of different communities to absorb environmental impacts and afford costs is becoming increasingly differentiated. Ecological restoration Because of historical decisions, much ecological work is needed for environmental restoration in cities and in poor and minority communities. Ecosystem management Knowledge of sources, reservoirs, sinks, flow, and drivers would be useful in understanding and predicting April 2007 163 Contributions environmental impacts, particularly for EJ pollution issues. Habitat alteration and destruction Perhaps the most ecologically devastating natural disaster in recent times has resulted in numerous publica- tions, most of which, like “In the Wake of the Storm: Environment, Disaster, and Race After Katrina” include professors affiliated with the disciplines of economics, Latin American and Latino Studies, sociology, and envi- ronmental studies/community health, but not ecology. An understanding of the role of ecology in land subsid- ence, wave impact, and loss of shoreline, to cite but a few examples, is so critical that its absence all but assures incomplete and incorrect solutions. Ozone depletion and climate change As Nancy Cole pointed out (2002), people of color and poverty tend to live downhill and downstream—and will be among those most affected by rising water levels—as was so clearly seen last August in New Orleans. They, and the very young and very old, are also the least able to afford and tolerate extreme temperatures. Species extinction and loss of biological diversity It should go without saying that biodiversity is affected by poverty and development. Thus, conservation plans must provide alternatives to harvesting of animals for bushmeat and the pet trade industry. Further, the im- pact of people is expected to increase in latent risk hot spots (Cardillo 2006). Natural resource management The recent debates (see for instance, Shellenberger and Nordhaus’ (2004) “The death of environmentalism,” Foreman’s (2006) “Take back the conservation movement,” and McCauley’s (2006) “Selling out on nature” as examples) focus on differences between conservationism, preservationism, and environmentalism—all within the context of their relation to humans, the built environment, resource needs and methods of extraction. While we cannot solve the differences, we can make a case that an understanding of fundamental ecological principles are critical for bridging the chasms and perhaps resolving some of these differences. (See for instance the UNEP Green Cities Declaration (2005) which resolves “…to build an ecologically sustainable, economically dynamic, and socially equitable future… .”) Sustainable ecological systems With Adams et al. (2004) recognizing that “the creation of protected areas can have substantial negative im- pacts on local people,” one cannot but envision difficulties in establishing successful and sustainable protected areas absent consideration of the surrounding human communities. One of us was asked recently whether EJ isn’t just another form of applied ecology. Indeed, it probably is, or certainly a case could be made for this—and that isn’t necessarily bad. The recent ESA Visions Report (2004) noted that “ecological knowledge must underpin the decisions that affect ecological sustainability … at all lev- els of society worldwide.” Turner (1996) pointed out that “If an ecosystem can’t be known or controlled with scientific data, then why don’t we can all the talk of ecosystem health and integrity and admit, honestly, that it’s just public policy, not science.” We don’t believe that it’s all about public policy, but do contend that without 164 Bulletin of the Ecological Society of America https://www.researchgate.net/publication/51370569_Biodiversity_Conservation_and_the_Eradication_of_Poverty?el=1_x_8&enrichId=rgreq-a8f3aaf1f24590f82e5fb33605a09e02-XXX&enrichSource=Y292ZXJQYWdlOzI1MDA3ODIzMTtBUzozMjcxNDc5NjYyMjIzMzZAMTQ1NTAwOTU2MTMzOQ== Contributions consideration of the public in developing policy, we are not likely to achieve any reasonable long-term success. Environmental justice is one framework that not only looks promising, but is the right thing to do. Keep in mind that while scientists identify, develop, and provide solutions to problems, implementation of these involves the public and politics. Acknowledgments This article represents a summary of introductory remarks for the “Linking Ecology and Environmental Jus- tice” symposium at the 2006 ESA Annual Meeting in Memphis, Tennessee. Organizers: George Middendorf (Howard University), Charlie Nilon (University of Missouri-Columbia), and Leanne Jablonski (Marianist Envi- ronmental Education Center). Literature cited Adams, W. M., R. Aveling, D. Brockington, B. Dickson, J. Elliott, J. Hutton, D. Roe, B. Vira, and W. Wolmer. 2004. Biodiversity conservation and the eradication of poverty. Science 306:1146–1149. Cherrett, J. M. 1989. Key concepts:The results of a survey of our members’ opinions. Pages 1–16 in J. M. Cher- rett, editor. Ecological concepts: the contribution of ecology to an understanding of the natural world. Black- well, Oxford, UK. Corburn, J. 2002. Combining community-based research and local knowledge to confront asthma and subsis- tence-fishing hazards in Greenpoint/Williamsburg, Brooklyn, New York. Environmental Health Perspectives 110 (supplement 2):241–248. Corburn, J. 2005. Street science: community knowledge and environmental health justice. MIT Press, Cam- bridge, Massachusetts, USA. Foreman, C. H. 1998. The promise and peril of environmental justice. Brookings Institution Press, Washington, D,C., USA. Foreman, D. 2006. Take back the conservation movement. International Journal of Wilderness 12:4–31. McCauley, D. J. 2006. Selling out on nature. Nature 443:27–28. Spirn, A. W. 2000. The language of landscape. Yale University Press, New Haven, Connecticut, USA. Spirn, A. W. 2005. Restoring Mill Creek: landscape literacy, environmental justice and city planning and design. Landscape Research 30:395–413. Turner, J. 1996. The abstract wild. University of Arizona Press, Tucson, Arizona, USA. George Middendorf Department of Biology Howard University Washington, DC 20059 (202) 806-7289 E-mail:gmiddendorf@howard.edu Charles Nilon Department of Fisheries and Wildlife Sciences University of Missouri-Columbia Columbia, MO 65211-7240 (573) 882-3738 E-mail: nilonc@missouri.edu April 2007 165 mailto:gmiddendorf@howard.edu mailto:nilonc@missouri.edu https://www.researchgate.net/publication/11435255_Combining_community-based_research_and_local_knowledge_to_confront_asthma_and_subsistence-fishing_hazards_in_GreenpointWilliamsburg_Brooklyn_New_York?el=1_x_8&enrichId=rgreq-a8f3aaf1f24590f82e5fb33605a09e02-XXX&enrichSource=Y292ZXJQYWdlOzI1MDA3ODIzMTtBUzozMjcxNDc5NjYyMjIzMzZAMTQ1NTAwOTU2MTMzOQ== https://www.researchgate.net/publication/11435255_Combining_community-based_research_and_local_knowledge_to_confront_asthma_and_subsistence-fishing_hazards_in_GreenpointWilliamsburg_Brooklyn_New_York?el=1_x_8&enrichId=rgreq-a8f3aaf1f24590f82e5fb33605a09e02-XXX&enrichSource=Y292ZXJQYWdlOzI1MDA3ODIzMTtBUzozMjcxNDc5NjYyMjIzMzZAMTQ1NTAwOTU2MTMzOQ== https://www.researchgate.net/publication/11435255_Combining_community-based_research_and_local_knowledge_to_confront_asthma_and_subsistence-fishing_hazards_in_GreenpointWilliamsburg_Brooklyn_New_York?el=1_x_8&enrichId=rgreq-a8f3aaf1f24590f82e5fb33605a09e02-XXX&enrichSource=Y292ZXJQYWdlOzI1MDA3ODIzMTtBUzozMjcxNDc5NjYyMjIzMzZAMTQ1NTAwOTU2MTMzOQ== https://www.researchgate.net/publication/274515474_The_Promise_and_Peril_of_Environmental_Justice?el=1_x_8&enrichId=rgreq-a8f3aaf1f24590f82e5fb33605a09e02-XXX&enrichSource=Y292ZXJQYWdlOzI1MDA3ODIzMTtBUzozMjcxNDc5NjYyMjIzMzZAMTQ1NTAwOTU2MTMzOQ== https://www.researchgate.net/publication/274515474_The_Promise_and_Peril_of_Environmental_Justice?el=1_x_8&enrichId=rgreq-a8f3aaf1f24590f82e5fb33605a09e02-XXX&enrichSource=Y292ZXJQYWdlOzI1MDA3ODIzMTtBUzozMjcxNDc5NjYyMjIzMzZAMTQ1NTAwOTU2MTMzOQ== https://www.researchgate.net/publication/255617472_Take_Back_the_Conservation_Movement?el=1_x_8&enrichId=rgreq-a8f3aaf1f24590f82e5fb33605a09e02-XXX&enrichSource=Y292ZXJQYWdlOzI1MDA3ODIzMTtBUzozMjcxNDc5NjYyMjIzMzZAMTQ1NTAwOTU2MTMzOQ== https://www.researchgate.net/publication/6831998_Selling_out_on_nature?el=1_x_8&enrichId=rgreq-a8f3aaf1f24590f82e5fb33605a09e02-XXX&enrichSource=Y292ZXJQYWdlOzI1MDA3ODIzMTtBUzozMjcxNDc5NjYyMjIzMzZAMTQ1NTAwOTU2MTMzOQ== https://www.researchgate.net/publication/256058649_The_Language_of_Landscape?el=1_x_8&enrichId=rgreq-a8f3aaf1f24590f82e5fb33605a09e02-XXX&enrichSource=Y292ZXJQYWdlOzI1MDA3ODIzMTtBUzozMjcxNDc5NjYyMjIzMzZAMTQ1NTAwOTU2MTMzOQ== https://www.researchgate.net/publication/253282486_Restoring_Mill_Creek_Landscape_Literacy_Environmental_Justice_and_City_Planning_and_Design?el=1_x_8&enrichId=rgreq-a8f3aaf1f24590f82e5fb33605a09e02-XXX&enrichSource=Y292ZXJQYWdlOzI1MDA3ODIzMTtBUzozMjcxNDc5NjYyMjIzMzZAMTQ1NTAwOTU2MTMzOQ== https://www.researchgate.net/publication/253282486_Restoring_Mill_Creek_Landscape_Literacy_Environmental_Justice_and_City_Planning_and_Design?el=1_x_8&enrichId=rgreq-a8f3aaf1f24590f82e5fb33605a09e02-XXX&enrichSource=Y292ZXJQYWdlOzI1MDA3ODIzMTtBUzozMjcxNDc5NjYyMjIzMzZAMTQ1NTAwOTU2MTMzOQ== https://www.researchgate.net/publication/51370569_Biodiversity_Conservation_and_the_Eradication_of_Poverty?el=1_x_8&enrichId=rgreq-a8f3aaf1f24590f82e5fb33605a09e02-XXX&enrichSource=Y292ZXJQYWdlOzI1MDA3ODIzMTtBUzozMjcxNDc5NjYyMjIzMzZAMTQ1NTAwOTU2MTMzOQ== https://www.researchgate.net/publication/51370569_Biodiversity_Conservation_and_the_Eradication_of_Poverty?el=1_x_8&enrichId=rgreq-a8f3aaf1f24590f82e5fb33605a09e02-XXX&enrichSource=Y292ZXJQYWdlOzI1MDA3ODIzMTtBUzozMjcxNDc5NjYyMjIzMzZAMTQ1NTAwOTU2MTMzOQ== Howard University From the SelectedWorks of George Middendorf March, 2007 ESA and Environmental Justice work_ctd5okul7jbdbngknlu5vi5vxm ---- Editorial: Stumbling Towards Climate Justice UPFRONT Editorial: Stumbling Towards Climate Justice Arthur Muliro Wapakala1 Published online: 31 July 2017 � Society for International Development 2017 Stories about climate change and its unfolding effects as well as the political drama surrounding the global process to arrest it, and hopefully give humanity a chance fill the pages of our newspapers, the screens of blog posts and so on. It is fair to say that there is a growing awareness that the climate is going to be central to the future of humanity. But even as a committed bandwagon of climate deniers continues to challenge the idea that humans are responsible for global warming, they remain a minority - albeit one that is well funded and politically connected and whose agenda is ostensibly that to upend the efforts being made to arrest climate change. But there are many sides to the stories of climate change: whereas a lot of ink is spent in describing the vicissitudes of the Paris Climate Agreement and the maneuvering around it, the stories that attract less attention are those of the human lives that have been caught up in the vortex of a changing climate. Granted, the world’s media houses tend to focus on the ‘big story’ and more often than not, the lives of peasants in the Sahel, fisherfolk in the Bay of Bengal or First Nation peoples in the North America affected by a rapidly changing and often unpre- dictable climate do not make the headlines, nor do they necessarily attract the attention of the decision makers in the various global fora that are discussing the climate and what to do about it. This does not make their plight any less important: on the contrary - it is perhaps from their lives and stories that we need to begin reflecting on why urgent actions are needed to try and reverse the current trajectory of global warming. Like the canary in the coal mine, their stories and experiences are perhaps a sentinel of what awaits us if we tarry in our quest. Their pleas for assistance, and most important, justice fall largely on deaf ears, per- haps because either we are convinced that their lives and livelihoods are marginal and expendable, or because we believe that by retrofitting our industries and our econo- mies, we can continue along the same trajectory that has preoccupied our planners for pretty much the last couple of centuries. In other words, we think we can continue to maintain our current and aspired lifestyles without too much of a course correction. If we are to survive this current challenge to our species, it can only be through a set of radical adjustments that force us back towards being in greater synchronicity with nature. But this is a difficult proposition to articulate and to swallow. Already, the much-heralded Paris Climate Agreement, whilst having obtained the signatures of over 190 countries does not challenge, or address the questions around why it became necessary to have this agreement in the first place and proceed along a path of understanding how to walk backwards from this point. Many will argue that pursuing such a path would make it impossible to have the agreement at all - and they are probably right. There are too many countries with too great a stake in the present architecture of economy and power to contemplate any- thing different. But then, is this not analogous to treating the symptoms of the problem and pretending that a cause does not exist? Courage needs to be found to address the root causes of the climate crisis and to discuss what we - as a species - want to do about it. To address the climate crisis, we need to talk about the prevailing models of production - but also how they are linked to inequality, discrimination and injustice around the world. In her & Arthur Muliro Wapakala amuliro@sidint.org 1 Rome, Italy Development (2016) 59:189–194 DOI 10.1057/s41301-017-0124-7 http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1057/s41301-017-0124-7&domain=pdf http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1057/s41301-017-0124-7&domain=pdf article, Audrea Lim argues that the ‘limitless economic growth and endless consumption that lie at the heart of capitalism’ are 1 the key drivers of today’s climate crisis. And she is not alone - there is a growing number of critics who excoriate the Paris approach and its silence around the need to tackle the key drivers of the climate crisis. Steffen Böhm of the University of Essex has suggested that the limitations of the current negotiation process ‘result from the current ‘carbon fetishism’, in which even emissions are commodified in an event to maintain the economic status quo 2 ’. In this view, the elephant in the room remains ‘the fundamental failure of neoliberal capitalism, as the world’s dominant economic system, to confront its hunger for exponential growth of production and consumption that has been made possible by the unique energy density of fossil fuels, such as coal, oil and gas’. In his article, he refers at length to the Belgian geographer Erik Swyngedouw remarking thus: ‘For him, capitalism’s attempt to deal with the cli- mate crisis is a perfect example of ‘post-politics’, generating a lot of talk about what needs to change to make our existence on earth sustainable – such as at the current Paris climate summit – without there much changing at all. What’s important to bear in mind though is that this talk about change is not all there is. Swyngedouw also argues that capital attempts to materially reconfigure itself through the crisis of climate change, precisely by turning through the crisis of climate change, precisely by turning carbon (nature) into a commodity. And of course, this must be seen in line with the commodification pro- cesses that have always been part of capitalism’s history’. 3 Writing about the impact of ‘capitalist economics’ on Indigenous peoples and communities, Kyle Powys Whyte has argued that they face climate risks largely because of how colonialism, in conjunction with capitalist economics worked to shape the geographic spaces they inhabit and subsequently their socio-economic conditions. ‘The consequences of capitalist economics, such as deforestation, water pollution, the clearing of land for large scale agriculture and urbanization, generate immediate disruptions on ecosystems, ‘rapidly’ ren- dering them very different from what they were like before, undermining Indigenous knowledge systems and Indigenous peoples’ capacity to cultivate land- scapes and adjust to environmental change… Yet what is more insidious about climate injustice against Indigenous peoples is that the settler institutions such as those of containment, that inflicted environmental change in the past, are the same institutions that fostered carbon-intensive economic activities on Indigenous territories. That is, containment strategies, such as removal of Indigenous peoples to reservations or the forced adoption of corporate government structures, all facilitated extractive industries, defor- estation and large-scale agriculture’. (Whyte 2017) American journalist Christian Parenti begins his book with the graphic description of the aftermath of a cattle raid in north-western Kenya and provides us with the context of this raid that left one Ekaru Loruman dead. We are told that persistent severe drought had led to encroachment of the Turkana, a pastoralist community, onto the lands of their Pokot neighbours and reciprocal raids to replenish stocks depleted by the droughts were increasingly common. He asks: ‘Why did Ekaru Loruman die? […] We could say tradition killed Ekaru, the age-old tradition of ‘stock- theft’, cattle raiding among the Nilotic tribes of East Africa. Or we could say he was murdered by a specific man, a Pokot from the Karasuk. Or that Ekaru was killed by the drought. When the drought gets bad, the raiding picks up. Or perhaps Ekaru was killed by forces yet larger, forces transcending the specifics of this regional drought, this raid, this geography and the Nilotic cattle cultures. To my mind… Ekaru’s death was caused by the most colossal set of events in human history: the catas- trophic convergence of poverty, violence and climate change’. (Parenti 2011: 4–5) In 2015, a Dutch district court sitting in The Hague ruled that the Dutch government had a legal duty of care towards current and future generations to lower its CO2 emissions. This landmark ruling - known as the Urgenda Case - was ‘the first case in which regular citizens have managed to hold their government accountable for taking insufficient action to keep them safe from dangerous climate change. The ruling stipulated that the ‘Dutch government is required to reduce its emissions by at least 25% by the end of 2020 (compared to 1990 levels). This means that the Dutch government is now, effective immediately, forced to take more effective action on climate change. It is also the first case in the world in which human rights are used as a 1 Audrea Lim, True Climate Justice Puts Communities of Color First, https://www.thenation.com/article/true-climate-justice-puts-commu nities-of-color-first/. 2 Steffen Böhm: The Paris Climate Talks and other Events of Carbon Fetishism, https://www.versobooks.com/blogs/2372-steffen-bohm- the-paris-climate-talks-and-other-events-of-carbon-fetishism. 3 Steffen Böhm: The Paris Climate Talks and other Events of Carbon Fetishism, https://www.versobooks.com/blogs/2372-steffen-bohm- the-paris-climate-talks-and-other-events-of-carbon-fetishism. 190 A. M. Wapakala https://www.thenation.com/article/true-climate-justice-puts-communities-of-color-first/ https://www.thenation.com/article/true-climate-justice-puts-communities-of-color-first/ https://www.versobooks.com/blogs/2372-steffen-bohm-the-paris-climate-talks-and-other-events-of-carbon-fetishism https://www.versobooks.com/blogs/2372-steffen-bohm-the-paris-climate-talks-and-other-events-of-carbon-fetishism https://www.versobooks.com/blogs/2372-steffen-bohm-the-paris-climate-talks-and-other-events-of-carbon-fetishism https://www.versobooks.com/blogs/2372-steffen-bohm-the-paris-climate-talks-and-other-events-of-carbon-fetishism legal basis to protect citizens against climate change 4 ’. This case and the subsequent ruling (although under appeal by the Dutch government) has inspired similar cases in Belgium, Norway and France. How then does the idea of justice play out henceforth? Justice for the Indigenous people who have seen their ancestral lands devastated? Or for Ekaru Loruman’s fam- ily? Or those Dutch citizens who fear for this and future generations? Or for the many other cases which we have not cited? Justice, in many of our countries, is often sought and not always obtained. So why add climate justice to the pot? Ultimately, it is because climate justice - and justice more generally - is a function of who we are and what we value. Most Western philosophers have generally regarded justice as fundamental for ordering interpersonal relations as well as establishing and maintaining a stable political society. In our case, we are perhaps more concerned with the latter part, the emphasis on having a stable political society – an outcome that is by no means guaranteed. As Peter Burnell wrote: ‘If the economic adjustment costs imposed by climate change or the financial costs of miti- gation and adaptation are distributed unevenly in society – to the detriment of politically weak groups - the chances of reaching the democratic norm of political equality become more remote. Not just climate change but also some of the efforts to address it can lead to social injustice harming at minimum democracy’s substance and reputation’. (Burnell 2012: 821) Thus, albeit a sensible proposition, the notion of climate justice remains a thorny one to implement nonetheless. As Rebecca Hall put it: Climate justice includes a focus on the root causes of climate change and making the systemic changes that are therefore required, a commitment to address the disproportionate burden of the climate crisis on the poor and marginalized, a demand for participatory democracy in changing these systems which require dismantling the fossil fuel corporate power structure, and a commitment to reparations and thus a fair distribution of the world’s wealth. 5 In his landmark Encyclical ‘Laudato Sı̀’ published in 2015, Pope Francis made an impassioned plea for climate justice suggesting that there is a need to go beyond the current palliative measures being implemented. In particular, he placed the asymmetry of power at the heart of the debate: ‘Climate change is a global problem with grave implications: environmental, social, economic, polit- ical and for the distribution of goods. It represents one of the principal challenges facing humanity in our day. Its worst impact will probably be felt by developing countries in coming decades. Many of the poor live in areas particularly affected by phenomena related to warming, and their means of subsistence are largely dependent on natural reserves and eco- systemic services such as agriculture, fishing and forestry. They have no other financial activities or resources which can enable them to adapt to climate change or to face natural disasters, and their access to social services and protection is very limited. For example, changes in climate, to which animals and plants cannot adapt, lead them to migrate; this in turn affects the livelihood of the poor, who are then forced to leave their homes, with great uncertainty for their future and that of their children. There has been a tragic rise in the number of migrants seeking to flee from the growing poverty caused by environmental degradation. They are not recognized by international conventions as refugees; they bear the loss of the lives they have left behind, without enjoying any legal protection whatsoever. Sadly, there is wide- spread indifference to such suffering, which is even now taking place throughout our world. Our lack of response to these tragedies involving our brothers and sisters points to the loss of that sense of responsibility for our fellow men and women upon which all civil society is founded. Many of those who possess more resources and economic or political power seem mostly to be con- cerned with masking the problems or concealing their symptoms, simply making efforts to reduce some of the negative impacts of climate change. However, many of these symptoms indicate that such effects will continue to worsen if we continue with current models of production and consumption. There is an urgent need to develop policies so that, in the next few years, the emission of carbon dioxide and other highly polluting gases can be drastically reduced, for example, substituting for fossil fuels and developing sources of renewable energy’. 6 This question of power asymmetries and how they are reproduced has to be a central element of climate justice campaigns going forward. We cannot talk of rethinking the current structures of production without rethinking how power within societies is managed and distributed. If the quest for climate justice is to have any success, it will need 4 The Urgenda Climate Case Explained http://www.urgenda.nl/en/ climate-case/. 5 Rebecca Hall, Defining Climate Justice, http://www.peacefulupris ing.org/defining-climate-justice-20130521. 6 Encyclical Letter Laudato Sı̀ of the Holy Father Francis on Care for Our Common Home, pp. 20–21. Editorial 191 http://www.urgenda.nl/en/climate-case/ http://www.urgenda.nl/en/climate-case/ http://www.peacefuluprising.org/defining-climate-justice-20130521 http://www.peacefuluprising.org/defining-climate-justice-20130521 to embrace a broader and more radical analysis of why we are in the funk we are today, and to rethink and reimagine a different outcome. As John Riddell (referring to the North American situation, but one whose message is nonetheless universal) put it quite succinctly: ‘The climate justice movement has insisted on a focus on communities most directly impacted by climate change, the marginalized and indigenous peoples. But for such an alliance to be effective it also requires building a working class environmen- talism that challenges capitalist production and the endless accumulation that necessarily entails eco- logical degradation. Unfortunately, ecological acti- vism in North America – even when confronting climate change – relies on market measures and utopic visions of green capitalism’. 7 As Albert Einstein remarked, ‘We cannot solve our prob- lems with the same level of thinking that created them’. So, what is the pathway that we must follow to at least try and embed climate justice at the centre of the conversations around climate change? It is necessary that we take a sys- temic and encompassing view that brings questions of inequality, continued oppression, gender discrimination and human rights into these conversations. This provides us with an opportunity to ‘reshape our economic system, and to create real alternatives to the profit-driven, fossil fuel–de- pendent system of white, corporate capitalism 8 ’. And in so doing, we will also need to challenge the power centres that continue to drive global warming. This means recognizing that the vast majority of emissions today derive from industry and agribusiness. It will call for a recasting of the narrative that promotes growth and consumption at all costs. The fact remains that there are no easy propositions or solutions. We have reached the point we are at through a prolonged and systematic period in which the primary goal of modern economic systems was growth and profit. This twin obsession neglected the ecological basis on which it thrived and it naturalized inequalities, patriarchy, violence and alienation as its core byproducts. As individuals, we might be compelled to take those actions that we believe will contribute to greater sustainability and hence be part of ‘making the difference’ to save the planet. Yes, these small actions are in their own right necessary and important, but this is not where we should be focusing our attention. Simple living will never be enough and will never be a substitute for the larger system change and reset that we should be craving for. So we are caught on the horns of a dilemma - one for which for most, the easier alternative is to adopt the ostrich’s strategy of burying our heads in the sand and hoping that the problem will go away. Derrick Jensen thinks we have been caught up in a double bind which he describes thus: ‘A double bind is where you’re given multiple options, but no matter what option you choose, you lose, and withdrawal is not an option. At this point, it should be pretty easy to recognize that every action involving the industrial economy is destructive (and we shouldn’t pretend that solar photovoltaics, for example, exempt us from this: they still require mining and transportation infrastructures at every point in the production processes; the same can be said for every other so-called green technology). So if we choose option one — if we avidly participate in the industrial economy — we may in the short term think we win because we may accumulate wealth, the marker of ‘‘success’’ in this culture. But we lose, because in doing so we give up our empathy, our animal humanity. And we really lose because indus- trial civilization is killing the planet, which means everyone loses. If we choose the ‘‘alternative’’ option of living more simply, thus causing less harm, but still not stopping the industrial economy from killing the planet, we may in the short term think we win because we get to feel pure, and we didn’t even have to give up all of our empathy (just enough to justify not stopping the horrors), but once again we really lose because industrial civilization is still killing the planet, which means everyone still loses. The third option, acting decisively to stop the industrial econ- omy, is very scary for a number of reasons, including but not restricted to the fact that we’d lose some of the luxuries (like electricity) to which we’ve grown accustomed, and the fact that those in power might try to kill us if we seriously impede their ability to exploit the world — none of which alters the fact that it’s a better option than a dead planet. Any option is a better option than a dead planet’. 9 As stated earlier, we are not left with many other options on the table other than to come up with new forms of politics that challenge the structural basis of our current economic models as well as current efforts to seek commercial opportunities in the climate crisis - which will simply be another way of continuing the ruin and disenfranchisement that have accompanied the present system to date. To return to Böhm’s argument, ‘climate 7 John Riddell, Climate vandalism and North American capitalism, https://johnriddell.wordpress.com/2017/06/07/climate-vandalism- and-north-american-capitalism/. 8 Audrea Lim, True Climate Justice Puts Communities of Color First, https://www.thenation.com/article/true-climate-justice-puts-commu nities-of-color-first/. 9 Derrick Jensen, Forget Shorter Showers, https://orionmagazine.org/ article/forget-shorter-showers/. 192 A. M. Wapakala https://johnriddell.wordpress.com/2017/06/07/climate-vandalism-and-north-american-capitalism/ https://johnriddell.wordpress.com/2017/06/07/climate-vandalism-and-north-american-capitalism/ https://www.thenation.com/article/true-climate-justice-puts-communities-of-color-first/ https://www.thenation.com/article/true-climate-justice-puts-communities-of-color-first/ https://orionmagazine.org/article/forget-shorter-showers/ https://orionmagazine.org/article/forget-shorter-showers/ justice is not something that should come after us accepting climate capitalism. A proper just climate can only be brought about if we don’t shy away from questioning the fundamental logic of carbon fetishism and the logic of the market that attempts to appropriate, commodify and financialize nat- ure’. 10 Getting to this point will require heroic efforts by women and men around the world to get out of their familiar comfort zones and, in words of Jensen, ‘remember that the role of an activist is not to navigate systems of oppressive power with as much integrity as possible, but rather to confront and take down those systems’. This journal brings together a number of viewpoints and perspectives on how questions of climate justice are seeing and addressed from different vantage points. The twenty- five contributors take us through a kaleidoscope of per- spectives that taken together, give a picture of the com- plexity of the challenge on the one hand; and on the other, a sense of the actions and proposals that are being worked on around the world. Virtually all the authors agree that the most vulnerable victims of climate change are found in the poorest countries of the world where there is also the least capacity to put together an adequate and sufficient response to the ravages of climate change. In her article, Miren Gutierrez gives us an overview of ‘the good, the bad and the ugly’. She analyzes the politics around the commitments to the Paris Agreement and where the different signatories stand with respect to their emission targets as well as the politics around the Green Climate Fund. Julian Brave NoiseCat argues for Indigenous peoples and their knowledge regimes to be acknowledged and given a greater role in the climate mitigation process. There is a need, he argues, for indigenous rights to be broadened and strengthened in order for them to stave off the challenges coming from fossil fuel development, extractive industries and the resultant climate change. Ruth Nyambura reminds us of the persistent disconnect between the formal processes at the state level and the realities on the ground, and how this is leading to the emergence of a network of transnational cli- mate, food and energy justice movement(s) that are working together to try and provide viable alternatives to those local communities hit by a perfect storm of multiple and inter- secting crises of climate change. We are told that there is a growing and hardening fissure between the elitist narratives of climate justice and climate action and the alternative visions of society that are being nurtured and worked upon at the grassroots. Julia Puaschunder, makes a proposal as to how to how to share the benefits and burdens of climate change in a fair and just manner within society, between countries and over time. She presents and discusses innovative compensation schemes such as climate bonds to spread the burden of climate change more equally between today’s and tomorrow’s society. Kelly McFarland looks at environmental factors driving migration and proposes a set of ‘guiding principles’ that could form the basis for a new, and different conversation on the imperatives of contem- porary migration and what policies might be pursued in this regard as well as some of the challenges that are likely to be faced in implementing the new policies. He decries the fact that the current political environment is ill-prepared to tackle complex, globally-based and humanitarian focused issues and challenges us to work towards building resilience within communities and to focus on the longer-term, adap- tive policies geared toward slow-onset migration and urbanization. Gabriel Ferrero urges us to get behind the 2030 Development Agenda and the related Sustainable Devel- opment Goals as this, together with the Paris Agreements offers a substantive framework to deliver on climate justice and to overcome inequalities, poverty, lack of hope and the erosion of human rights, underlying root causes of insecu- rity, conflicts, and forced migration. He reminds us that our common destiny imposes on us the need to cultivate shared values and principles; shared goals and targets and above all shared responsibility and action by all actors. Lorna Gold challenges International Non-Governmental Development Organizations (INGDOs) not to contribute to the conspiracy of silence which still surrounds climate change in Western societies by ignoring it in their campaigns and advocacy. She argues that they have a privileged role to help shifting the public narrative on climate change and climate justice at a national level where they operate through the stories and experiences they can help leverage to bring the reality of the global scale of climate injustice into national contexts where the impacts may not be readily understood. Bertrand Noiret reflects on the challenge of ensuring food security and adequate nutrition in a world with a rapidly changing cli- mate. He suggests that these twin goals be at the centre of climate change actions and calls for strengthened repre- sentation and participation of social movements and non- government organization, at relevant fora as well as closer coordination and cooperation amongst those institutions working on food security and nutrition. Tristan Quinn-Thi- bodeau and Brandon Wu reflect on the challenges that a Donald Trump presidency brings with it for NGOs and cli- mate activists in the United States. They suggest that larger NGOs need to break out of their silos and engage with and support grassroots, frontline, and social movement leader- ship, fighting on issues not traditionally associated with stopping climate change. The current political context, in their view, offers a real opportunity for development NGOs to take a principled stand and actively take sides with the people they purport to serve even if these postures should prove to be uncomfortable. Isis Alvarez and Simone Lovera 10 Steffen Böhm: The Paris Climate Talks and other Events of Carbon Fetishism, https://www.versobooks.com/blogs/2372-steffen- bohm-the-paris-climate-talks-and-other-events-of-carbon-fetishism. Editorial 193 https://www.versobooks.com/blogs/2372-steffen-bohm-the-paris-climate-talks-and-other-events-of-carbon-fetishism https://www.versobooks.com/blogs/2372-steffen-bohm-the-paris-climate-talks-and-other-events-of-carbon-fetishism argue for the need to mainstream gender in climate change actions as this could lead to new policy actions that enhance women’s participation in tackling biodiversity loss and cli- mate change. They tell us that the patriarchal system has so far marginalized women in implementing biodiversity and climate commitments and remind us that we need to discard stereotypes of women being ‘weak’ and ‘dependent’ and recognize that historically, women have been key agents in leading societal change. The above and the other sterling contributions in this issue challenge us collectively to reflect on the entity of the problem that climate change poses, and why ultimately, we will have to adopt a climate justice approach. As individual readers, we may not always agree with the suggestions that the authors have made or the solutions that are being implemented. Theirs are ideas to provoke conversations and to remind us that the challenges that climate change will unleash will stretch our collective imagination and test our institutions - locally and internationally in ways that perhaps they were never made to. If there is but one lesson to draw from this anthology, it is that nothing is static in a time of intense turmoil. We will look to different spheres of achievement for solutions - be they technical, social or spiritual. What we cannot do is run away from the fact that attaining climate justice; resolving the climate crisis will be in the final analysis a political challenge. In the earlier part of this editorial, I repeatedly made the point that we will need to find ways and means to go beyond the limits of the current capitalistic model of production and consumption. We will need to figure out how to challenge its foundations and to think of what can replace it - and some suggestions are made in the following articles. Wean ourselves off the dependency on fossil fuels. Tackle the waste of industrial agriculture. Rethink our models of resilience. And so on. In concluding, we will need to find a way of ensuring that the dialogue that is necessary does not become hostage to denialism, or what David Roberts has called ‘tribal epistemology’ in which: ‘Information is evaluated based not on conformity to common standards of evidence or correspondence to a common understanding of the world, but on whe- ther it supports the tribe’s values and goals and is vouchsafed by tribal leaders. ‘‘Good for our side’’ and ‘‘true’’ begin to blur into one’. 11 The current challenge calls for collaboration, not senseless competition. It requires that we work together to enlarge the common ground from which we can begin to search for lasting solutions as opposed to creating islands of righ- teousness. If we are to find viable solutions and outcomes to our predicament, it will require that we find ways and means of reinforcing trust at all levels of society. This means that we will have to accept that predominant narratives are challenged and that spaces for alternative narratives are cultivated. Many have called ours ‘the age of possibilities’ - humanity, with its technological progress and achieve- ments of the past centuries seemed to have reached the cusp of going beyond what were hitherto considered the limits to our progress as a species. And we have achieved a lot. But we are now discovering that nature is a powerful adversary, and not necessarily a forgiving one either. ‘Never before have the possibilities of a good world for the human species as a whole been greater. At the same time, the gap between human potential and the existing conditions of humankind in its totality has probably never been wider. Ours is also an age of extremes. What stands in between the potential and the actual are the economics of environmental destruction and social exclusion of whoever is not profitable, the economics, sociology and psychology of inequality, the power politics of division and war. No end to all of this is in sight. However, a species consciousness is emerging, in particular one of environmental challenges but also of human rights and human potential’. (Therborn 2016: 37) We are now called upon to take a step back and look at everything in perspective. A course correction may yet be possible - time is running out, but we still have a limited window to make that difference. References Burnell, Peter. 2012. Democracy, democratization and climate change: complex relationships. Democratization 19 (5): 813–842. Parenti, Christian. 2011. Tropic of Chaos: Climate Change and the New Geography of Violence. New York: Nations Books. Therborn, Göran. 2016. An Age of Progress? New Left Review No. 99 May–June. Whyte, Kyle Powys. 2017. Is it Colonial Déjà Vu? Indigenous Peoples and Climate Injustice. In Humanities for the environ- ment: Integrating knowledges, forging new constellations of practice, ed. J. Adamson, M. Davis, and H. Huang, 88–104. London: Earthscan Publications. 11 David Roberts, Donald Trump and the rise of tribal epistemology, https://www.vox.com/policy-and-politics/2017/3/22/14762030/ donald-trump-tribal-epistemology. 194 A. M. Wapakala https://www.vox.com/policy-and-politics/2017/3/22/14762030/donald-trump-tribal-epistemology https://www.vox.com/policy-and-politics/2017/3/22/14762030/donald-trump-tribal-epistemology Editorial: Stumbling Towards Climate Justice References work_ctv46udfszfozd42wsccaq4hdq ---- http://coa.sagepub.com Critique of Anthropology DOI: 10.1177/0308275X05058656 2005; 25; 389 Critique of Anthropology Daniel M. Goldstein Flexible Justice: Neoliberal Violence and ‘Self-Help’ Security in Bolivia http://coa.sagepub.com/cgi/content/abstract/25/4/389 The online version of this article can be found at: Published by: http://www.sagepublications.com can be found at:Critique of Anthropology Additional services and information for http://coa.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts Email Alerts: http://coa.sagepub.com/subscriptions Subscriptions: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navReprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navPermissions: http://coa.sagepub.com/cgi/content/refs/25/4/389 SAGE Journals Online and HighWire Press platforms): (this article cites 20 articles hosted on the Citations © 2005 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 10, 2008 http://coa.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://coa.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts http://coa.sagepub.com/subscriptions http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav http://coa.sagepub.com/cgi/content/refs/25/4/389 http://coa.sagepub.com Flexible Justice Neoliberal Violence and ‘Self-Help’ Security in Bolivia Daniel M. Goldstein Rutgers University, USA Abstract ■ As Bolivia has restructured its economic and political sectors accord- ing to a neoliberal model, citizens have been required to become more ‘flexible’ in securing their livelihoods, creating ‘self-help’ economic activities and informal employment schemes to make ends meet. At the same time, as state mechanisms for administering justice and producing ‘security’ fail due to the inadequacies of the neoliberal regime, Bolivian citizens are adopting ‘flexible’ attitudes toward crime and punishment, frequently turning to ‘self-help’ justice mechanisms (including private security patrols and vigilante lynchings) to combat crime in their communities. This article explores the processes by which neoliberal logic and language condition the experiences and responses to crime and insecurity of residents in different neighborhoods of Cochabamba, Bolivia. It suggests that lynchings in Bolivia today be understood as a kind of neoliberal violence, produced both by the scarcities and deficiencies of the privatizing state, and by the logic of transnational capitalism itself, which has saturated civil society and public culture. Keywords ■ Andes ■ Bolivia ■ neoliberalism ■ transnationalism ■ vigilantism ■ violence In the second week of October 2003, a week that marked the anniversaries of both the Columbian ‘discovery’ of the New World and 21 years of Bolivian democracy, the Bolivian state massacred 62 people in violent confrontations in and around the nation’s capital, La Paz, and neighbor- ing El Alto (Opinión, 2003c). The massacres occurred in the context of the so-called ‘Gas War’, a massive social protest joined by peasant groups, labor unions, coca farmers, and the urban poor, against the Bolivian govern- ment’s plans to export natural gas through a Chilean port for sale to the United States. Fearing that once again, as has happened so many times in the neoliberal era, a vital component of the Bolivian ‘national patrimony’ was to be expropriated by foreign interests, this loose coalition of indigen- ous and labor groups took to the streets, demanding cancellation of the gas sale and the resignation of Bolivia’s president, Gonzalo Sanchez de Lozada.1 The bloodiest confrontation between protestors and the state occurred on 12 October, when heavily armed police and military units attempting to escort gasoline trucks past a blockade in El Alto fired live Article Vol 25(4) 389–411 [DOI:10.1177/0308275X05058656] Copyright 2005 © SAGE Publications (London, Thousand Oaks, CA and New Delhi) www.sagepublications.com © 2005 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 10, 2008 http://coa.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://coa.sagepub.com ammunition into a crowd of people challenging this action. In response to these killings, protestors’ calls for the president’s resignation escalated, while blockades, marches, and demonstrations gained momentum throughout the country. Despite international support, the president’s ruling coalition crumbled in the face of continued domestic unrest, and Sanchez de Lozada fled the country a few days later.2 As human rights scholars and activists have discovered (e.g. Godoy, 2002), democratic governance does not automatically produce a rule of law and a respect for human rights, a fact that has become painfully clear to Bolivians and students of the Bolivian sociopolitical landscape in recent years. Though officially a democracy since 1982 – when a democratically elected regime replaced the military ‘narco-dictatorship’ of General Luis García Mesa, ending decades of authoritarian rule in the country – Bolivia has struggled to implement democratic political and legal reform while contending with the requirements of neoliberal structural adjustment and the globalization of capital. The Bolivian state, a star pupil of the neoliberal school, has diligently complied with the demands of international lending agencies and foreign nations (especially the United States), restructuring its economy to provide a more favorable climate for multinational invest- ment, privatizing national industries and slashing state payrolls and programs, while watching unemployment rise and poverty worsen for the majority of the national population (Kohl, 2002).3 State efforts to impose these political and economic mandates have sometimes been accompanied by violence, both by and against the state and its representatives. Indeed, as the violence of the Gas War reveals, Bolivian society today, though formally democratic, is more violent than ever: according to the Bolivian Permanent Human Rights Assembly (Asamblea Permanente de Derechos Humanos), more Bolivians were killed by the state in 2003 than during any year of the military dictatorships (AIN, 2003). The Gas War violence continued in 2005, as protestors again took to the streets to demonstrate against the unresolved issues surrounding privatization and expropriation of natural gas, again willing to invoke the wrath of the state to protest neoliberal policies relating to the nation’s most valuable natural resource.4 These violent events and continued unrest have their roots in the Bolivian state’s efforts to comply with foreign pressures and structural adjustment programs encoded in transnational strategies of political and economic reorganization, and thus represent forms of ‘neoliberal violence’ (cf. Auyero, 2000). Neoliberal violence is at once structural and undeniably physical; it entails an inequitable distribution of resources within a rigidly hierarchical society, which ultimately must be implemented and main- tained by state violence, and which in turn engenders violent responses. This violence is quotidian – it marks the everyday lives of poor, marginal- ized (and, in Bolivia, indigenous) people, creating a profound sense of insecurity, an anxious and fearful ‘structure of feeling’ (Williams, 1977) that colors every aspect of daily existence – and in moments of rupture like 390 Critique of Anthropology 25(4) © 2005 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 10, 2008 http://coa.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://coa.sagepub.com the Gas War, it can be shockingly bloody. It also transcends the geographi- cal and ideological space of the nation-state, being motivated by and pursuant to the demands of a transnational political-economic regime that reconfigures national policies and programs according to its own logic of privatization, ‘responsibilization’, and ‘flexibility’ (Harvey, 1991; Ong, 1999). In the economic restructuring that underlies it and the reduced capacity of the state to provide services that this restructuring creates, neoliberal violence produces violations not only of the political and civil rights of individuals, but of their social and economic rights as well. I put forth the idea of neoliberal violence because I want to use it as a frame for interpreting yet another kind of violence currently ongoing in Bolivia, one that I think must be viewed within this same, broader context of neoliberalism and the rights violations it engenders if it is to be properly understood. I am referring to the lynching of thieves by groups of residents in many urban neighborhoods throughout Bolivia, but particularly centered in the southern zone of Cochabamba, Bolivia’s third largest city. While exact numbers are difficult to come by, my own research (supple- mented by that of Acción Andina, 2003) has documented hundreds of such incidents in and around Cochabamba over the last five years (Goldstein, 2003). As I discuss below, lynching has proliferated in Cochabamba and elsewhere in Bolivia in conjunction with the nation’s overall economic decline, and as people’s vulnerability to violence, official corruption, and criminal predation has escalated. My attempt in this article to understand lynching violence should not be misconstrued as an effort to rationalize or justify it. Without a doubt, lynching represents an indefensible form of violence, a violation of the most basic rights of human beings. And yet, what I want to suggest here is that these lynchings be understood not in isolation from the ongoing violence produced by the Bolivian state, but in concert with it. The spate of lynchings occurring in Cochabamba and other locations across Bolivia is generated by and in reaction to transnational violence that is at once structural, physical, and all pervasive in Bolivia today. Far from the spon- taneous expressions of an innately primitive and anti-democratic nature (a common interpretation of lynching, as I will discuss in more detail below), lynchings are collective expressions of rage and despair in a context of total vulnerability, not only to crime but to the ravages of a political-economic order that disproportionately and prejudicially impacts poor and indigen- ous people. Facing mounting violence and crime, unemployment and a sense of powerlessness to confront a sociopolitical order that ignores their demands for economic, legal, and social justice, these people respond with violence, in a futile effort to control crime and as a response to the nation- state’s neglect of their own rights to justice and security in their communi- ties. At the same time, the form and the logic of vigilante justice in Bolivia today is profoundly shaped by and expressive of certain basic principles of neoliberalism itself. In particular, the ‘privatization’ of justice reflects key 391 Goldstein: Flexible Justice: Neoliberal Violence in Bolivia © 2005 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 10, 2008 http://coa.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://coa.sagepub.com organizational – indeed, cultural – themes of neoliberal political economy, and rather than working to reduce lynching violence, the national state and its transnational underwriters, as principal proponents of the logic of flexibilization and privatization, can actually be viewed as co-conspirators in its elaboration. I thus suggest that lynchings in Bolivia today be under- stood as a kind of neoliberal violence, produced both by the scarcities and deficiencies of the kind of ‘sclerotic state’ (Speed and Reyes, 2002) that neoliberalism precipitates, and by the logic of transnational capitalism itself, which has saturated civil society and public culture. In this analysis of the articulations between global capitalism and local violence, the nation-state emerges as a key player: rather than being rendered irrelevant by globalization (as some critics have suggested – see the discussion in Comaroff and Comaroff, 2001), the nation-state becomes a critical site through which global economic and cultural flows are managed and deployed, an instrumental actor that maintains the conditions of capitalist profitability and, through its policies, regulatory requirements, and interpolation of local subjectivities (what analysts are now commonly calling its techniques of governmentality, following Foucault, 1991; Merry, 2001), the state instantiates capitalism’s cultural logic in the daily administrations of national life (Robinson, 2004). And it is the state that is the principal point of articulation between global forces and local actors, who respond to the pressures and potentials of globaliz- ation, sometimes as willing collaborators, at other times in violent protest against the similarly violent transformations it engenders. In what follows, I examine some of the most critical cultural and political components of this transnational articulation, focusing on ideas about privatization, flexi- bility, and justice that not only have local impacts, but that are continually managed and reworked by local actors attempting to establish a sense of security for themselves in the highly unstable social field of late capitalism.5 In the next section of this article, I provide a summary description of lynching in Cochabamba, with reference to the larger discursive frame- works within which it is typically interpreted. I then go on to suggest that lynching be understood as part of a larger practice of violence that pervades neoliberal society, and in fact partakes of the fundamental logic of ‘flexi- bility’ that lies at its heart. The next section of the article discusses other forms of ‘privatization of justice’ in Bolivia, including police corruption and private police firms, suggesting further linkages between neoliberal economic logic and the provision of security in the contemporary Bolivian city. In the conclusion, I analyze these various forms of violence and security provision within the broader context of neoliberal capitalism, with sugges- tions for how this discussion can affect our understandings of global and local linkages in contemporary society. 392 Critique of Anthropology 25(4) © 2005 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 10, 2008 http://coa.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://coa.sagepub.com Lynching violence in Bolivia The vigilante lynching of criminal suspects has become a common practice in the marginal barrios of Bolivian cities, with the majority of such incidents being reported in the southern zone of Cochabamba. As I have described elsewhere (Goldstein, 2003, 2004), one of the first of these lynchings occurred in one such barrio (Villa Sebastián Pagador) in 1995, when I was there doing fieldwork. In that event, three individuals were caught red- handed robbing a home in broad daylight, and were nearly lynched by a crowd of angry residents. When the police finally arrived, dressed in riot gear, to disrupt the lynching, people attacked the advancing police cordon until the police dispersed the crowd with tear gas.6 This near-lynching, as it turns out, was an early forerunner of what has since become a common practice of collective violence by the residents of marginal barrios all around Cochabamba. According to reports that I and my colleagues in Acción Andina have collected from police sources, social service agencies, and local newspapers, literally hundreds of lynchings or attempted lynch- ings have occurred in Cochabamba during the last five years. Indeed, events of this kind have occurred with such frequency in the popular barrios of Cochabamba and elsewhere that, according to a recent report, Bolivia ranks second in the world (behind Guatemala) in the number of lynchings that have taken place (Opinión, 2003a).7 Lynchings have occurred with such frequency in Cochabamba that they have become routinized, and unfold according to their own ritual schema. Typically in these incidents, a criminal suspect (usually a supposed thief, child molester, or some other kind of felon or petty criminal) is appre- hended by a group of local residents, who are quickly joined by other inhabitants of the zone. This group ties up the suspect, and subjects him (or sometimes her) to verbal and physical abuse, which can include beating, hair cutting, and stoning. Sometimes these tortures lead to death, as the suspect is doused with gasoline and set on fire by the angry mob. More often than not, however, the police arrive to rescue the lynching victims or otherwise disrupt the event. In most cases, both the victims and the perpetrators of lynching violence are of indigenous origin (Quechua and/or Aymara), and belong to the poorest, most marginal sectors of Bolivian society. As the next section of this article discusses in more detail, lynch mob participants in Cochabamba typically justify their violence as a response to rising crime in their neighborhoods and the apparent inability or unwillingness of the authorities to police their communities effectively.8 The sudden upsurge in lynchings since 2000 is not, I would argue, coincidental. Popular rage against the neoliberal state, brewing since the implementation of the New Economic Policy (state decree 21060) in 1985, began to crystallize and find expression around the turn of the millennium. Significantly, 2000 was the year the ‘Water War’ erupted in Cochabamba (Farthing and Kohl, 2001). A large-scale popular uprising in response to 393 Goldstein: Flexible Justice: Neoliberal Violence in Bolivia © 2005 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 10, 2008 http://coa.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://coa.sagepub.com the Bolivian state’s attempt to privatize the water supply system in that city, the Water War forced the cancellation of the state’s contract with the multi- national Bechtel corporation, an event that was internationally hailed as a popular victory in the struggle against globalization (Finnegan, 2002). Several economic shocks also may have contributed to the rising tide of popular violence in Cochabamba at around this same time. The relatively successful coca-eradication program (the so-called Plan Dignidad) initiated in 1997 during the presidency of General Hugo Banzer had by 2000 begun to severely impact the regional economy of Cochabamba, as many families lost a longstanding source of informal income. Additionally, the Argentine economic crisis negatively affected the Cochabamba economy, as thousands of migrants were forced to return home and families dependent on foreign remittances lost a considerable portion of their income. By 2000, people in Cochabamba had become poorer and increasingly frustrated with a priva- tizing state whose promises of greater prosperity for all had clearly failed to materialize.9 Despite its many connections to contemporary political economy, local media accounts typically frame the lynching violence on Cochabamba’s south side as acts of savagery, committed by people who lack a basic respect for democracy and civilized society. Bolivian newspaper commentaries frequently denounce lynching as ‘an attack on social institutions’ (Los Tiempos, 2001) that threatens to unravel the fabric binding the human community together. Lynchings are described as ‘primitive and cruel’, an embarrassment for a nation striving for modernity and progress: ‘The lynchings make Bolivia one of the most backward countries on earth,’ remarks one editorial writer (Opinión, 2002). ‘The image of Bolivia, of all of us, should not be marked by the primitive conduct of certain groups of people.’ Another columnist characterized lynchings as acts of ‘primitive barbarism’, asserting that they are symptoms of ‘social degradation’ that suggest that Bolivian society ‘is losing the fundamental values that are needed to build a democratic society’ (Opinión, 2003b). Lynchings are described as a brake on national progress and an obstacle to democratic advancement. From the perspective of analysts who produce the formal public discourse about the meaning of lynchings in Bolivia, it is the lynch- ings themselves that are the cause, rather than an expression, of the failure of democracy in Bolivia today.10 By labeling lynching a survival of some bygone era whose practitioners themselves are retrograde, the practice and its perpetrators are made to stand as representatives of a predemocratic past that now serves as an anchor weighing on national political develop- ment.11 In reading such accusations, however, the fact cannot be overlooked that those being so characterized are indigenous Quechua and Aymara people, and that indigenous people in the Andes have long been depicted in terms similar to those being used to describe lynchings and lynch mobs in Bolivia today – as retrograde and primitive, threats to orderly urban life 394 Critique of Anthropology 25(4) © 2005 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 10, 2008 http://coa.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://coa.sagepub.com and to civilization itself. Since the colonial era, the very presence of indigenous Andeans in the urban landscape has been considered a viola- tion of the nation’s ‘racialized imaginative geography’ (Radcliffe and Westwood, 1996), which locates ‘Indians’ properly in the countryside, and ‘white’ or ‘mestizo’ populations in the city (Weismantel, 2001). In a similar fashion, indigenous rural-to-urban migrants in Cochabamba have long been perceived by the city’s white middle class (and by the institutions of media, government, and commerce that they control) as invaders, threats to the longstanding social and political order of the city (Goldstein, 2004). The poverty of these people has been characterized as bearing disease and contamination into the city (see Colloredo-Mansfeld, 1998; Douglas, 1966); their patterns of land invasion and spontaneous settlement have been viewed as attacks on the ‘rational’ and orderly growth of the city itself (Solares Serrano, 1986; Urquidi Zambrana, 1967, 1986). Accusations of ‘barbarism’ and antagonism towards democracy ascribed to lynching inter- sect with this enduring racist critique of indigenous urbanites, demonizing the actors without attempting to understand the context that makes their violence possible and predictable. Instead of regarding lynching as a barbaric survival from the past, I argue instead that lynching be understood in the context of neoliberal structural reform, within which it is embedded and from which it derives its logic and, in the minds of its perpetrators, its legitimacy. Lynching, in a sense, fulfills the highest mandates of neoliberal rationality: it represents the privatization of justice, the assumption by individuals of a service ordi- narily provided by the state, and so points to the increasing importance of ‘flexibility’ as a personal and communal survival strategy in neoliberal society. Lynching fills the gap left by the withdrawal of the state from the delivery of official justice, as citizens themselves take on the responsibility of creating security when the state will not. Given the state’s orientation toward responsibilization – the transfer of state functions to citizens and informal or non-governmental associations – lynching is the logical and indeed predictable response of people required to be flexible in providing for their own needs. Neoliberalism and the crisis of security Neoliberal economic reforms accompanying democratization throughout most of the ‘developing world’ were intended to create a more productive environment for transnational capitalism by removing barriers to trade and creating a ‘flexible’ workforce that could provide cheap labor to trans- national industries (Harvey, 2001). Flexibility is a critical dimension of late capitalism, part of the post-Fordist logic that allows corporations to maximize the turnover rate of capital by eschewing fixed production facili- ties and their associated labor costs, replacing these older, inflexible 395 Goldstein: Flexible Justice: Neoliberal Violence in Bolivia © 2005 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 10, 2008 http://coa.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://coa.sagepub.com relations of production with strategies of ‘outsourcing’, labor reorganiza- tion, and geographical mobility as part of a regime of ‘flexible accumu- lation’ (Harvey, 1990; Inda, 2000). Promising a more efficient economy that would create more and better jobs for national workers while curtail- ing state involvement in both market regulation and the social reproduc- tion of labor, neoliberalism has thoroughly displaced the developmentalist model that had for decades been the dominant approach to economic policymaking, shifting the emphasis in public discourse from national development to global competitiveness and efficiency (Arbona, n.d., a). Whereas in this earlier economic model the state was a major player in promoting national development by controlling market forces and guaran- teeing (at least rhetorically) jobs and social welfare for the poor, in the neoliberal era the state encourages the development of ‘self-help’ social and economic mechanisms, devolving responsibility for the maintenance of workers from the private sector and the state to local communities, non- governmental organizations, families, and individuals (Gill, 2000). These reforms have resulted in a measurable increase in economic inequality and a dramatic decrease in the standard of living for the rural and urban poor, as ownership of land and other resources has become further concen- trated, peasants have been dispossessed, and public sector jobs have dis- appeared (Gwynne and Kay, 2000; Lustig, 1995; Petras and Veltmeyer, 1999). Today at least 260 million people in Latin America live in poverty (Aiyer, 2001; Bulmer-Thomas, 1996; Chossudovsky, 1997). Within Latin America, Bolivia has been one of the most aggressive implementers of the neoliberal model. Since 1985, the Bolivian state has promoted policies that have withdrawn the state from direct participation in the national economy, privileging private sector firms as the engines of development and encouraging self-generation of employment for displaced workers (Benería, 1996; ILO, 2002). Virtually all nationally owned industries have been privatized (or ‘capitalized’, in the language of the system),12 the political potential of trade unions has been defused (García Linera, 1999), state programs and jobs have been cut, and the state itself has been ‘decentralized’, with the transfer of federal responsibilities to municipalities and non-governmental organizations (Kohl, 2003; Medeiros, 2001; Postero, 1999). In the realm of labor policy, Bolivia has emphasized a program of labor flexibilization (‘flexibilización laboral’), a mainstay of Bolivian economic policy since 1985. Being flexible in the Bolivian context means being willing to work on short-term contracts, in home-based industries, and, increasingly, in the informal economy, creating one’s own income-generating opportunities when the regular economy fails to provide work. Flexibility also means caring for oneself and one’s family by working without a net, that is, through self-employment without benefit of public provision of social security. In the language of Bolivian neoliberalism, these forms of flexibilización and responsibilización of individuals represent what sociologist Ulrich Beck (1992: 143) has 396 Critique of Anthropology 25(4) © 2005 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 10, 2008 http://coa.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://coa.sagepub.com identified as ‘a generalization of employment insecurity’ within post-Fordist capitalism, compounded by a complete sundering of the social reciprocity that capital and the state historically provided to labor. Flexibility and individual responsibility, then, are the watchwords of Bolivian society today, and the state has pursued specific policies that put these principles into practice. For example, the Bolivian state is a major proponent of privately owned micro-enterprises, small-scale business inter- ests intended to promote ‘economic democracy’ by generating new forms of employment, thereby providing market integration for the poor and marginalized (Rhyne, 2001). Micro-enterprise promotion positions the state as taking an active role in providing for its citizens, part of the state’s own attempt to stabilize neoliberalism through highly visible public policy initiatives intended to demonstrate its commitment to strengthening the domestic economy. But, as Arbona (n.d., b) points out, micro-enterprises in fact require very little investment or oversight on the part of the state, and serve to transfer social welfare responsibilities from the state to the working poor themselves. Micro-enterprises fulfill the demands of inter- national lenders in that they do not require the state to participate directly in the national economy, while promoting ‘individual responsibility as the only possibility for securing welfare’ (Arbona, n.d., b: 13). In the words of a Presidential decree on the subject of micro-enterprises, the Bolivian work- force is encouraged to be ‘flexible’, and to demonstrate ‘responsibility, creativity, and adaptability’ (Presidencia de la República de Bolivia, 1998; cited in Arbona, n.d., b) in generating employment in the face of the ongoing economic crisis. But the state offers no concrete alternatives when such enterprises fail, nor any material support to ensure that they do not. The economic insecurity created by neoliberal reforms is comple- mented by a physical insecurity resulting from rising crime rates that have accompanied structural adjustment, compounded by the deficiencies of an unreliable and inequitable system of official justice. For the upper class, police and judicial services are at least nominally available to investigate crimes, respond to grievances, and resolve conflicts. But for the majority of crime victims, who are typically poor and marginalized, honest and reliable police protection or recourse to the law are simply nonexistent. Instead, the poor themselves are often criminalized in public discourse and in police practice, and experience heightened police violence, as states adopt more repressive and violent measures in the name of crime control (Davis, 2003; Frühling, 2003; Méndez et al., 1999; Pereira and Davis, 2000; Schneider and Amar, 2003; Ungar, 2002). Even in the absence of direct experience of crime, the fear of criminal and state violence, perpetuated by ‘talk of crime’, ratchets up the levels of insecurity people confront and the extremes to which they are willing to go to attain security (Caldeira, 2000; Dammert and Malone, 2003; Elbert, 1998; Rotker, 2002). Especially in urban areas, a general feeling of fear and insecurity may seem all- encompassing and inescapable, part of the habitus of daily life (Garland, 397 Goldstein: Flexible Justice: Neoliberal Violence in Bolivia © 2005 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 10, 2008 http://coa.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://coa.sagepub.com 2001: 153; Merry, 1981). Facing widespread police corruption and violence, compounded by a generalized and apparently endless economic ‘crisis’, urban residents experience an overwhelming sense of ‘ontological insecurity’, a pervasive sense of despair and uncertainty that Anthony Giddens (1990) has identified as one of the defining conditions of late modernity. While neoliberal economic policy has become ubiquitous throughout Latin America since the mid-1980s, the hegemony of neoliberal philosophy has been far from absolute, the promised benefits of democratic and economic reform contradicted by the escalating poverty and violence of neoliberal society. Nevertheless, the themes of flexibility, privatization, and self-help individualism, so prominent within liberal capitalism, emerge as profound cultural forces that shape the behavior of national subjects, and in turn are shaped by them. As the ethnographic discussion in the next section of this article explores, this is particularly true in efforts initiated by poor urban Bolivians to establish ‘security’ in their communities. Aban- doned and victimized by the state and its policing and judicial apparatus, for many citizens the only viable option for obtaining security appears to be ‘self-help’ justice-making (for the most part, through lynching) to create some semblance of order in their community (though this strategy tends to perpetuate the cycle of violence within which poor communities are already ensnared). Rather than rely on the empty promises of the state and its official justice system, many residents of Cochabamba’s marginal barrios recognize the need to be ‘flexible’, to use ‘responsibility, creativity, and adaptability’ in pursuing ‘justice’ by other means. If the state will not provide work, people must create their own employment opportunities; similarly, if the state will not provide justice, punishing criminals becomes an individual responsibility. Taking the law ‘into one’s own hands’ has a very different resonance when understood in light of these larger, official discourses and practices, as the next section explores. ‘No hay justicia en Bolivia’ In February of 2001, a US Peace Corps volunteer in Bolivia named Walter Poirier disappeared somewhere in rural La Paz department. His body was never found, and no sightings of him have been reported. Despite urgings from the Peace Corps and the US State Department, the Bolivian police have been unable to produce any evidence related to Poirier’s disappear- ance or whereabouts. This incident has generated much commentary on the Peace Corps’ online discussion boards, including a posting from someone named ‘Nina’, who titled her contribution ‘THERE IS NO JUSTICE IN BOLIVIA’: I just read about the missing person Mr. Poirier. I feel sad that he disappeared in Bolivia. However if you want to find information about him, you have to go in person to La Paz. Please take professional people who can do the job from here. Because in Bolivia ‘the judicial system’ is non-existent. The authorities do 398 Critique of Anthropology 25(4) © 2005 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 10, 2008 http://coa.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://coa.sagepub.com not do their work and have no means to go from one place to another to inves- tigate. My brother was killed in La Paz, Bolivia on March 8, 2003. I went three times to La Paz to investigate his death. We did a necropsy and found out that he died because somebody hit him on the head causing hematomas. The Bolivian police did not do a reconstruction of the crime scene for five months. So I couldn’t get any finger prints or samples. The clothes he was wearing when they found him were thrown on the floor at the police station. The police does not have pictures of the autopsy. And after 2 months we found one sample of the gastric fluids taken from the autopsy. I was more outraged, when the police investigator that was assigned to my brother’s death was removed and re- assigned to another case of a rich person. They left my brother’s case without investigator for 5 months . . . At the end, they closed the case without solving it. The police does not have any chemicals when they investigate a crime scene, they don’t have paper to write reports, they do not have money to buy film to take pictures of the crime scene, and I had to pay transportation for the police workers whenever they needed to go and do something for my brother’s case. This terrible crime is unsolved, now for me the only solution is to complain to the human rights [representatives]. Because in Bolivia there is no justice for middle class or poor people. The police is so corrupt that for doing a simple thing they want money. I spent so much money in lawyers and bribing the police workers to do their job. (http://PeaceCorpsOnline.org/messages/messages/ 2629/2013899.html; sic) The failure of the state to provide adequate security and an accessible justice system to its people has been one of the key sources of state delegit- imation in Bolivia today, and pertains directly to the neoliberal restructur- ing of the nation so visibly denounced in the Gas War. Even as the national crime rate quadrupled between 1993 and 1999, the overall budget for the Bolivian national police force shrank; most of that budget was allocated toward purchasing equipment rather than hiring or training police officers. In 1999, the police budget was reduced by 25 percent and in each year since has been cut by an equal or greater percentage of the remaining total (Ungar, 2003: 34). The lack of police protection is particularly evident in urban areas, which have expanded rapidly over the last few decades, again in response to neoliberal reforms that closed the nationally owned mining sector and otherwise jeopardized rural livelihoods, propelling people to the cities. In Cochabamba, for example, fewer than 1000 police officers are assigned to protect a population of nearly 800,000 residents;13 fewer than a dozen police vehicles are deployed in the city, while a fleet of police motorcycles sits idle, the department lacking funds to buy gasoline to run them. The investigative capacity of the Cochabamba branch of the national police force is similarly weak: police lack the training and material resources to collect and preserve evidence, and to follow up leads effec- tively. The police morgue is a veritable house of horrors, with the cadavers of crime victims left to decompose in the open air for periods of up to three weeks, the authorities lacking refrigeration facilities and medical personnel to perform expedient autopsies. Forensics departments are understaffed, 399 Goldstein: Flexible Justice: Neoliberal Violence in Bolivia © 2005 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 10, 2008 http://coa.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://coa.sagepub.com and lack even the most basic equipment (including rubber gloves and surgical instruments) to go about their work in a manner that guarantees the validity of evidence obtained (Herrera G., 2003). Officially, crime rates in Bolivia increased 140 percent per year between 1995 and 2002 (Conte, 2003b), though most crimes go unreported due to citizens’ complete lack of faith in the police institution’s ability to investi- gate and arrest criminal suspects. People of all social classes in Cochabamba attribute this failure to the deep and extensive corruption that permeates the Bolivian police and legal professions, a result of the poor salaries paid to justice professionals (a street officer earns under $1300 a year) and the ever-present temptation to profit from one’s contacts with criminal networks (Ungar, 2003). Human rights activists argue that corruption actually serves to maintain the police force as an institution: in the absence of adequate public funding, the force relies on the money its officers skim or extort from the criminals they apprehend to allow them to purchase such mundane necessities as gasoline. The recent, highly publicized Blas Valencia scandal – which revealed the existence of a corrupt ‘mafia’ of high- level officers based mostly in La Paz but extending to other cities as well – seemed to confirm the credibility of accusations claiming that corruption is pervasive throughout the police establishment.14 This perception comes through clearly in interviews I have conducted with groups of residents from different social classes, genders, and occu- pations in marginal neighborhoods of Cochabamba city. Many people echo Nina’s testimony, above, asserting that the police are inept and corrupt, and that the administration of justice favors the rich over the poor and the middle class. ‘The police are terrible,’ reported one woman, a coordinator of an artisan’s group in the city.15 ‘There is no justice in Bolivia. At least for the poor there isn’t. You have to have money to get justice.’ Many people contend (like Nina) that the police will not investigate unless the complainant pays them to. People report that the police demand money to pay for the costs of routine investigations: The first thing they ask for in the PTJ [Policía Técnica Judicial] is money. My niece was murdered and when we went to the police so that they would inves- tigate, the first thing they asked us for was $100 to begin the investigation. Imagine how much they would want to complete the investigation! Because we didn’t have money, we had to leave it at that. She was killed, she was buried, but nothing. Another artisan recounted her own experience of being robbed, and going to report the crime to the police: I go into the PTJ, which at that time was operating out of the main plaza, I go in and, ‘Yes, I recognize him, there he is.’ They have photos of those offenders (malhechores) all over the place in there, and I go, ‘That’s him,’ I say. . . . ‘Ahh! Of course that’s him, señora, tomorrow we’ll go and recover [the money]. But only half.’ ‘Okay,’ I said, ‘half.’ I accepted, no? Such blackmail! But I accepted, half. And to this day I haven’t gotten my half. 400 Critique of Anthropology 25(4) © 2005 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 10, 2008 http://coa.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://coa.sagepub.com The sense of powerlessness that people derive from their encounters with police colors their view of official justice more generally, and shapes their understanding of their own subordination within the broader sociopoliti- cal arena. In the words of another artisan: It seems to me that our hands are tied, that we can’t do anything, we don’t have the power. Those that are in power, yes, they can do and undo things . . . but society can’t do anything because we don’t have the power, we don’t have the political power, we don’t have the economic power, so if we protest it is all in vain . . . Many people confronting this situation of vulnerability and powerless- ness see a direct link between police corruption and neglect and the impulse to take the law into their own hands. In Villa Sebastián Pagador, on Cochabamba’s far southeastern fringe, a group of women described what happened after a crime was committed in the barrio in 1995. Here, lynching is described as the direct result of police inaction and corruption: Señora 1: There is a denunciation, the police come, they take notes, notes, that’s it, then the thing is forgotten. If you don’t put down any money, there is no investigation. Señora 2: That’s why we make justice with our own hands, too, sometimes we tie him up, like that time when the residents here . . . Señora 1: They burned him. The logic behind this self-help administration of justice becomes even more evident when considered in light of two other kinds of privatization of security – police corruption and the rise of private policing – that have also intensified in the neoliberal era. Privatization and corruption The extortion of crime victims and their families by the national police represents another form of Bolivian privatization, in this case the privatiza- tion of public functions by the very personnel charged with their execution. Police corruption converts the public administration of justice into a private resource that maintains both individual police officers and, ironi- cally, the police institution itself. Corrupt officers turn the police investi- gation into a form of prospecting (what economists call ‘rent-seeking behavior’; Kohl, 2004; Krueger, 1974), using their authority to pursue indi- vidual profit, while paying kickbacks to officers higher up the ladder who naturally turn a blind eye to such proceedings. The police department further encourages this ‘entrepreneurial’ behavior, both to cover its insti- tutional costs and to turn a profit for its operatives. Encounters between private citizens and public officials like those described above thus consti- tute a double victimization for those who report crimes to the police – first 401 Goldstein: Flexible Justice: Neoliberal Violence in Bolivia © 2005 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 10, 2008 http://coa.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://coa.sagepub.com at the hands of criminals, and then at those of the police themselves, all of whom operate according to a code of profit maximization at the expense of the poor. A 1999 study of the Bolivian national police issued by an external review panel (composed of officers and representatives of the Colombian police force) described the police institution as ‘a bunker whose operation is concentrated to a large degree, in attending to individ- ual interests related to illicit enrichment, the granting of favors to groups from outside the institution, and the obtaining of a higher social position through the ranks of the police hierarchy’ (Los Tiempos, 2003). However, official knowledge of the problem has not led to any changes in police procedure or oversight of the daily management of the institution, and no action has been taken on the Colombian report. For poor Cochabambinos, official denials of corruption stand as another indication that there is no reliable public sector to which they can appeal for redress of grievances. People typically do not report most crimes to the police, realizing that it will not be likely to result in any action being taken, and to the contrary may end up costing them more than the original offense that they have suffered. For some, this state of affairs translates directly into individual responsibility and an impulse to take matters into their own hands. Said Cochabamba resident: ‘I also have this attitude of lynching, because I don’t see any other way, that the laws, that the judicial organizations offer a real solution to handling delinquents. . . . Especially, there is no solution within the justice [organizations], each person has to make his own justice.’ The police themselves generally concur with the assessment that they are unable to control crime or police the barrios. Privately, individual police officers confess a certain sympathy for the lynchings, which commonly occur in barrios where they themselves reside. My friend Fausto Huanca, for example, a low-ranking street officer in the national police force and a resident of Villa Pagador, is deeply ashamed of the corruption revealed by the Blas Valencia scandal, and considers it a black mark on an otherwise decent profession. At the same time, Don Fausto is a member of a force deeply stratified along class and racial lines. For the most part, members of the officer corps tend to be classified as ‘white’ in the national racial hier- archy, a distinction that generally correlates with a middle- or upper-class income, background, and lifestyle. Ordinary police officers of the lower ranks like Don Fausto, on the other hand, tend to be categorized as indigenous and poor. Like Don Fausto, they live in the barrios rather than in the city center or the better suburbs, and so are themselves vulnerable to the same kinds of criminal predation as their neighbors. Trained in the service of a police force that is both nationalistic and resolutely masculine, men like Don Fausto espouse a rhetoric of law that places the exercise of control and violence solely in the hands of the ‘legally constituted authori- ties’. But they also recognize that these authorities are themselves corrupt, and as barrio residents they share the critique of the police held by the 402 Critique of Anthropology 25(4) © 2005 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 10, 2008 http://coa.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://coa.sagepub.com majority of their neighbors. The low-level policemen recognize that they are underpaid and typically called upon to do the dirtiest jobs of repres- sion and control, but they also embrace this work as their duty as citizens and as men (compare with Gill’s [2000] study of the Bolivian military). They thus regard lynching as a problem and an inevitability. Don Fausto, for example, condemns lynching as a crime, an inappropriate exercise of force that must be prosecuted to the fullest extent of the law. On the other hand, he is highly sympathetic towards the lynch mob and its aims, and is reluctant to criticize the actions of people who are, in matter of fact, his friends, relatives, and neighbors. Other private forms of policing and law enforcement have also emerged in recent years, which put a prettier face on vigilante justice while partici- pating in the same logic and similar techniques as the lynching. In Cochabamba today, more than 100 private security firms have been created to provide private police services to all those willing to pay.16 Though origi- nally confined to the wealthier zones of the city, today these security firms can be found in most parts of Cochabamba, filling in for the absent state in poor barrios throughout the city. In Villa Pagador, for example, residents of a barrio sector known as Segundo Grupo contribute one boliviano (approx- imately 15 US cents) per day to pay for a security patrol on the main avenue running through their zone. Private security firms like this one are often founded and managed by retired military or police officers, entrepreneurs schooled in violence and corruption who take advantage of the need for their services created by deficiencies in the very institutions they formerly served. Firms exploit the general climate of fear and insecurity created by rising crime and state inadequacy to generate business for themselves. On the street where I live in Cochabamba, for example, the local security provider (a firm with the witty English-language name ‘Bolivian Pest Control’) puts out a monthly newsletter in which they report on various cases of police inadequacy in Cochabamba, citing newspaper articles to that effect; they also offer their clients suggestions on how to improve home security, including such helpful tips as: ‘Every time you enter or leave your dwelling, secure the door with two turns of the lock and put on the security chain and if you have another lock use that one, too’ and ‘Women and young ladies should avoid drying their underwear in visible places and should not wear scanty clothing on balconies or in front of windows, in case a sex maniac is watching.’ Fear mongering of this sort represents yet another kind of structural violence, one generated by the neoliberal state and exploited by private firms that have arisen in its absence. While many people profess a satisfaction with the services provided by the private security firms, others are less sanguine. They point to the fact that the young men these firms employ to patrol the streets are oftentimes themselves former criminals, recently released thieves and others familiar with the ins and outs of the local crime scene and the Bolivian justice system. Many people whose neighborhoods are patrolled by these firms 403 Goldstein: Flexible Justice: Neoliberal Violence in Bolivia © 2005 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 10, 2008 http://coa.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://coa.sagepub.com claim that the private security providers are no better than the police, using their privileged position as uniformed thugs in the barrios to communicate with accomplices and rob the very homes they are supposed to protect. ‘In my barrio, near my aunt’s house,’ said one young woman, ‘where these very same private security guards are stationed, they spy out the house and inform others that they can enter, and they have gone into various houses, they have emptied out various houses in the barrio.’ Barrio residents who refuse to pay for the services of the neighborhood’s private firm may find their homes singled out for repeated burglaries and vandalism. After her home was robbed, apparently with the collusion of local private security officers whom she had been reluctant to pay, another friend who works as an architect for the Cochabamba municipal government confessed to me that, ‘Now I know how the lynch mobs feel.’ The security firms operate very much like a protection racket, carving the city up into turfs that different groups control, often using violence to punish criminal suspects whom they apprehend, to ward off competing firms encroaching on their territory,17 or to threaten recalcitrant clients. Though currently forbidden to carry firearms under Bolivian law, the firms are agitating Congress for this right, which they deem necessary to perform their functions; others fear that this will only hasten the evolution of these firms from mafias into full-blown paramilitaries, furthering the devolution of other state functions (i.e. the role of the military) to private enterprises and creating an additional threat to democratic stability in the process. Conclusion Neoliberal violence, including physical violence produced by the military, police personnel, private security guards, and lynch mobs, and the struc- tural violence of poverty and insecurity, are all grounded in the reforms of the neoliberal state and the cultural logic of privatization, flexibility, and self-help that accompanies them. The Bolivian state’s response to the lynching phenomenon is further indicative of this relationship. Even as it has formally denounced lynching as a threat to democratic society, the Bolivian state (in keeping with its broad neoliberal stance celebrating indi- vidual enterprise as an alternative to state involvement) has acted to encourage private and citizen’s groups to further adopt responsibility for justice administration. For example, just a few weeks prior to his forced resignation in 2003, President Sanchez de Lozada responded to increas- ingly strident calls for improved ‘citizen security’ in Bolivia by announcing a plan (never implemented) to create ‘anticrime gangs’ (pandillas anti- crimen) in various Bolivian cities. These gangs, officially known as ‘youth citizen security brigades’ (brigadas juveniles de seguridad ciudadana), would have consisted of young people who would patrol certain zones of the city, confronting other, criminal youth gangs and somehow preventing them 404 Critique of Anthropology 25(4) © 2005 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 10, 2008 http://coa.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://coa.sagepub.com from committing crimes. Decried by critics and human rights defenders as unleashing ‘a new war against society’ (Conte, 2003a), the president’s proposal was steeped in the logic of the liberal citizen, in which ‘good’ people would act independently and without state supervision to deter ‘bad’ people from committing antisocial acts. This same logic provides the foundation for the lynch mob, whose members view themselves as filling in for the absent state, pursuing ‘delincuentes’ and ‘malhechores’ who prey on the good people of society. Lost in this good/bad distinction is the fact that delincuentes and linchadores (lynch-mob participants) alike are poor people of indigenous origin, engaged in an escalating cycle of violence whose end is not currently in sight. The state’s embrace of this logic amounts to an endorsement of lynching as a mode of securing justice, which likewise requires no state supervision or state financing to execute. Neoliberalism, like the classical liberalism from which it is descended, has at its base a claim to promote individual freedom, a promise to liberate the individual from the inherently oppressive power of government (Anderson, 1992). The authors of 20th-century liberal capitalism, economists like F.A. Hayek (1944) and Milton Friedman (Friedman and Friedman, 1962), believed that only by restricting the state’s involvement in economic planning and management could the state’s coercive power be effectively limited. Economic regulation, in this view, imposes constraints on the basic liberty of the individual (said to be the cornerstone of Western civilization), thus requiring the separation of the economic from the political to create a freer and more democratic society. At the same time as it mandates the state’s withdrawal from the national economy, however, liberalism assumes that the state will provide the broader social and civic institutions within which capi- talism can function unfettered and individual liberty can be attained. This includes the establishment and maintenance of a democratic rule of law, to create a safe and stable society within which capital markets can flourish and individual potential can be achieved. Key to the entire system is a respect for individual rights and freedoms. According to liberalism’s proponents, by granting rights to individuals, and by respecting popular sovereignty and maintaining a rule of law to guarantee these rights, the state recognizes human dignity and promotes individual liberty (Fukuyama, 1992). In the name of such noble ideals, neoliberalism has become the dominant paradigm of 21st-century global political economy. But the contradiction between liberalism’s promise and its reality in Bolivia is manifest in the lives of people living under its dominion. Like police officers who at once condemn and sympathize with lynching violence in the barrios of Cochabamba, ordinary citizens demonstrate a contradictory consciousness when facing the insecurity of daily life in a neoliberal democracy. As the protests by members of the so-called ‘popular classes’ in both the Water War and the Gas War clearly indicate, people in Bolivia recognize that their poverty has its roots in transnational capitalism, and that the forces of privatization and the open market have had negative 405 Goldstein: Flexible Justice: Neoliberal Violence in Bolivia © 2005 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 10, 2008 http://coa.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://coa.sagepub.com impacts on their employment opportunities, standard of living, and access to basic services. Protesters who reject the privatization and expropriation of natural resources are articulating a critique of global political economy that accurately perceives the role of transnational forces in restructuring Bolivian social life, and which ultimately are responsible for their diminish- ing economic and personal security. As I have suggested in this article, however, at the same time as they stridently and publicly reject neoliberalism, in their communities ordinary Bolivians have adopted practices that clearly express and enact neoliberal rationality. The same cultural logic of individual responsibility, flexibility, and self-help that informs both Bolivian labor policy and the state’s approach to justice administration has pervaded civil society and its base communities, whose members privatize justice when the state refuses to treat it as a public good. This is the double-sided nature of what I have identified as neoliberal violence. Not merely an expression of the state’s commitment to protecting and defending the interests of capital, neoliberal violence is also structural violence, an inherent component of the neoliberal project and its associated cultural values, which underlie the general condition of insecurity that is both cause and result of popular violence. The ongoing Gas War has nakedly revealed the Bolivian state’s fundamental disregard for the rights of individuals when they challenge the state’s neoliberal schemes; the insecurity of daily life is a less visible, though equally destructive, form of violence, and as a source of social disarticula- tion it precipitates other forms of violence in their turn. Acknowledgements An earlier version of this article was presented at the 102nd annual meeting of the American Anthropological Association, Chicago, IL, 19–23 November 2003. Funding for this research was provided by a Grant for Research and Writing from the John D. and Catherine T. MacArthur Foundation, and by a Summer Faculty Fellowship from the College of the Holy Cross. For help and feedback on this paper, I wish to thank Juan Manuel Arbona, Leigh Binford, Jennifer Burrell, Philip Coyle, Angelique Haugerud, Billie Jean Isbell, Benjamin Kohl, Kathryn Ledebur, Sally Engle Merry, and Shannon Speed, as well as the editors and anonymous reviewers for Critique of Anthropology. Special thanks to Rose Marie Achá, Ana Laura Durán, Saúl García, Eric Hinojosa, and Theo Röncken for help with research and reflection on these ideas. Notes 1 Additionally, people were protesting the Nuevo Código Tributario, which restruc- tured national income taxes in such a way as to extract more wealth from the poor and middle classes, so as to generate money for foreign debt repayment; and the Ley de Seguridad Ciudadana, which prescribed long prison sentences for 406 Critique of Anthropology 25(4) © 2005 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 10, 2008 http://coa.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://coa.sagepub.com social protestors employing road blockades in their demonstrations. The security law also removed government funding for public illumination projects, a program that had benefited the marginal barrios of the nation’s cities whose streets are typically dangerous after dark. 2 The US government backed Sanchez de Lozada, calling on all Bolivians ‘to reject confrontation that could lead to violence and injury. The international community understands and supports the legitimate interests of all the Bolivian people, and we urge them to express and promote those only through demo- cratic and peaceful means’ (DOS Press Release, 15 October 2003). 3 Sanchez de Lozada, in his first (non-consecutive) term as president of Bolivia in the mid-1990s, was the principal architect of an economic and political restructuring scheme (the Plan de Todos) that systematized a program of private foreign investment in formerly state-owned enterprises; see Kohl (2003). 4 At the time of this writing in 2005, only one death has been officially attributed to the recent round of protests, though the regime of another Bolivian president, Carlos Mesa, has already fallen victim to them. 5 In this analysis, I follow Aihwa Ong (1999) in understanding globalization as the flow not only of capital, information, and people across national borders, but of the cultural logics that underpin post-Fordist capitalism and that profoundly impact, and are negotiated by, local populations. This approach aims to integrate, rather than bifurcate, the local and the global, the cultural and the political-economic. ‘Only by weaving the analysis of cultural politics and political economy into a single framework,’ Ong says, ‘can we hope to provide a nuanced delineation of the complex relations between transnational phenomena, national regimes, and cultural practices in late modernity. . . . An under- standing of political economy remains central as capitalism . . . has become even more deeply embroiled in the ways different cultural logics give meanings to our dreams, actions, goals, and sense of how we are to conduct ourselves in the world.’ (1999: 16) 6 A fuller account and analysis of this incident can be found in Goldstein (2003, 2004). 7 For considerations of lynching in other Latin American contexts, see Burrell (2002), Castillo Claudett (2000), Fuentes Díaz and Binford (2001), Guerrero (2001) and Vilas (2001). 8 Other similar incidents in more rural contexts include the executions of suspected cattle thieves in the Cochabamba valley, and the execution of the mayor of Ayo Ayo, an Aymara community on the Bolivian altiplano. This latter incident, though initially described as a lynching, later proved to be more of a mob-style execution, enacted by rival gangs in this town. 9 My thanks to Ben Kohl for his thoughts on these subjects. 10 Elsewhere (Goldstein, 2004) I have examined another emerging strain in the media analysis of lynching, which tends to be more sociologically grounded and sympathetic to the actions of lynch mobs. As the problems of the Bolivian economic crisis continue to mount, the media is becoming less openly condem- natory of lynching ‘savagery’. 11 This problem is also apparent in arguments (offered by some lynch mob partici- pants seeking to justify their actions by an appeal to ‘tradition’) that theorize lynching to be some sort of holdover from the rural past, a contemporary expression of older forms of traditional law (derecho consuetudinario). While 407 Goldstein: Flexible Justice: Neoliberal Violence in Bolivia © 2005 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 10, 2008 http://coa.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://coa.sagepub.com physical forms of punishment were not unknown in rural Andean contexts, contemporary urban lynchings represent distinct forms of violence that must be understood (I argue) within the current context of neoliberal reform. 12 For an explanation of the particulars of Bolivian ‘capitalization’ and a discussion of neoliberalism’s failure to create employment in that country, see Kohl (2002). 13 In contrast, for example, New York City has approximately one police officer for every 200 people (http://www.nyc.gov/html/nypd/home.html). 14 Of course, police and other forms of official corruption are not new in Bolivia (or anywhere else, for that matter), but have long been endemic in the political system. Police corruption has taken on a new urgency in the neoliberal era, however, as the next section of this article explores. 15 All translations of interviews and other texts, except where the original English is specified, are my own. 16 One is reminded here of Jane and Peter Schneider’s (2003) work on the Sicilian mafia. 17 Friends and interview subjects report the beginnings of turf wars between rival security firms, who use violence to establish and protect certain areas of the city as their own domains. References Acción Andina (2003) http://www.cedib.org/accionandina/index.php AIN (Andean Information Network) (2003) Tensions Continue to Mount in Bolivia’s ‘Gas War’. Aiyer, Ananthakrishnan (2001) ‘Hemispheric Solutions? Neoliberal Crisis, Criminal- ity and “Democracy” in the Americas’, Urban Anthropology and Studies of Cultural Systems and World Economic Development Summer–Fall: 239–52. Anderson, Perry (1992) A Zone of Engagement. London: Verso. Arbona, Juan Manuel (n.d., a) ‘Managing Policy Failures: Neo-liberal Tensions, Ruptures, and Stabilizations in El Alto, Bolivia’. Unpublished ms. Arbona, Juan Manuel (n.d., b) ‘Restructuring the Informal Economy: The State and the Promotion of Micro-enterprises in Bolivia’. Unpublished ms. Auyero, Javier (2000) ‘The Hyper-shantytown: Neo-liberal Violence(s) in the Argentine Slum’, Ethnography 1(1): 93–116. Beck, Ulrich (1992) Risk Society: Towards a New Modernity. London: Sage. Benería, Lourdes (1996) ‘The Foreign Debt Crisis and the Social Cost of Adjust- ment in Latin America’, in J. Friedmann, R. Abers and L. Autler (eds) Emer- gences: Women’s Struggles for Livelihood in Latin America, pp. 11–27. Los Angeles, CA: UCLA, Latin American Studies Program. Bulmer-Thomas, Victor (1996) The New Economic Model in Latin America and its Impact on Income Distribution and Poverty. New York: St. Martin’s Press. Burrell, Jennifer (2002) ‘Intimate Violence: After Lynching in Todos Santos Cuchu- matán’. Paper presented at the 101st annual meeting of the American Anthro- pological Association, 21 November, New Orleans. Caldeira, Teresa P.R. (2000) City of Walls: Crime, Segregation, and Citizenship in São Paulo. Berkeley: University of California Press. Castillo Claudett, Eduardo (2000) ‘La justicia en tiempos de la ira: Linchamientos populares urbanos en América Latina’, Ecuador Debate 51: 207–26. Chossudovsky, M. (1997) The Globalization of Poverty: Impacts of IMF and World Bank Reforms. London: Zed. 408 Critique of Anthropology 25(4) © 2005 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 10, 2008 http://coa.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://coa.sagepub.com Colloredo-Mansfeld, Rudi (1998) ‘“Dirty Indians’, Radical Indígenas, and the Political Economy of Social Difference in Modern Ecuador’, Bulletin of Latin American Research 17(2): 185–205. Comaroff, Jean and John L. Comaroff (2001) ‘Millennial Capitalism: First Thoughts on a Second Coming’, in J. Comaroff and J.L. Comaroff (eds) Millennial Capi- talism and the Culture of Neoliberalism, pp. 1–56. Durham, NC and London: Duke University Press. Conte, Gabriel (2003a) ‘Bolivia y sus “pandillas anticrimen”: Una nueva forma de guerra contra la sociedad’. La Paz: Desarme.org. URL (consulted September 2005): http://www.desarme.org Conte, Gabriel (2003b) ‘Para un especialista, el delito es “regulado” en Bolivia por la policía’. La Paz: Desarme.org. URL (consulted September 2005): http:// www.desarme.org Dammert, Lucia and Mary Fran T. Malone (2003) ‘Fear of Crime or Fear of Life? Public Insecurities in Chile’, Bulletin of Latin American Research 22(1): 79–101. Davis, Diane E. (2003) ‘Law Enforcement in Mexico City: Not Yet Under Control’, NACLA Report on the Americas 37(2): 17–24. Douglas, Mary (1966) Purity and Danger: An Analysis of the Concepts of Pollutions and Taboo. London, Boston and Henley: ARK. Elbert, Carlos Alberto (1998) ‘Ideología, corrupción y excesos policiales’, Pena y Estado: Revista Latinoamericana de Política Criminal 3(3): 63–80. Farthing, Linda and Benjamin Kohl (2001) ‘Bolivia’s New Wave of Protest’, NACLA Report on the Americas 34(5): 8–11. Finnegan, William (2002) ‘Leasing the Rain’, The New Yorker 8 April. Foucault, Michel (1991) ‘Governmentality’, in G. Burchell, C. Gordon and P. Miller (eds) The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality, pp. 87–104. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Friedman, Milton with Rose Friedman (1962) Capitalism and Freedom. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Frühling, Hugo (2003) ‘Police Reform and the Process of Democratization’, in H. Frühling, J.S. Tulchin and H.A. Golding (eds) Crime and Violence in Latin America: Citizen Security, Democracy, and the State, pp. 15–44. Washington, DC: Woodrow Wilson Center Press. Fuentes Díaz, Antonio and Leigh Binford (2001) ‘Linchamientos en Mexico: Una respuesta a Carlos Vilas’, Bajo el Volcán 2(3): 143–56. Fukuyama, Francis (1992) The End of History and the Last Man. New York: Free Press. García Linera, Alvaro (1999) Reproletarización: Nueva clase obrera y desarollo del capital industrial en Bolivia (1952–1998). La Paz: Muela del Diablo. Garland, David (2001) The Culture of Control: Crime and Social Order in Contemporary Society. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Giddens, Anthony (1990) The Consequences of Modernity. Cambridge: Polity. Gill, Lesley (2000) Teetering on the Rim: Global Restructuring, Daily Life, and the Armed Retreat of the Bolivian State. New York: Columbia University Press. Godoy, Angelina Snodgrass (2002) ‘Lynchings and the Democratization of Terror in Post-war Guatemala: Implications for Human Rights’, Human Rights Quarterly 24: 640–61. Goldstein, Daniel M. (2003) ‘“In Our Own Hands”: Lynching, Justice and the Law in Bolivia’, American Ethnologist 30(1): 22–43. Goldstein, Daniel M. (2004) The Spectacular City: Violence and Performance in Urban Bolivia. Durham and London: Duke University Press. Guerrero, Andrés (2001) ‘Los linchamientos en las comunidades indígenas: ¿La política perversa de una modernidad marginal?’, Ecuador Debate 53: 197–226. 409 Goldstein: Flexible Justice: Neoliberal Violence in Bolivia © 2005 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 10, 2008 http://coa.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://coa.sagepub.com Gwynne, Robert N. and Cristobal Kay (2000) ‘Views from the Periphery: Futures of Neoliberalism in Latin America’, Third World Quarterly 21(1): 141–56. Harvey, David (1990) The Condition of Postmodernity: An Enquiry into the Origins of Cultural Change. Oxford: Blackwell. Harvey, David (1991) ‘Flexibility: Threat or Opportunity?’, Socialist Review 21(1): 65–77. Harvey, David (2001) Spaces of Capital: Towards a Critical Geography. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. Hayek, F.A. (1944) The Road to Serfdom. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Herrera G., Herbert (2003) ‘Médicos forenses están abandonados a su suerte’, Los Tiempos (Cochabamba): C3. ILO (International Labor Organisation) (2002) Women and Men in the Informal Economy: A Statistical Picture. Geneva: ILO. Inda, Jonathan Xavier (2000) ‘A Flexible World: Capitalism, Citizenship, and Post- national Zones’, Political and Legal Anthropology Review 23(1): 86–102. Kohl, Benjamin (2002) ‘Stabilizing Neoliberalism in Bolivia: Popular Participation and Privatization’, Political Geography 21: 449–72. Kohl, Benjamin (2003) ‘Restructuring Citizenship in Bolivia: El Plan de Todos’, International Journal of Urban and Regional Research 27(2): 337–51. Kohl, Benjamin (2004) ‘Privatization Bolivian Style: A Cautionary Tale’, International Journal of Urban and Regional Research 28(4): 893–908. Krueger, Anne O. (1974) ‘The Political Economy of the Rent Seeking Society’, American Economic Review 64 ( June): 291–303. Los Tiempos (2001) ‘Linchamiento: Atacan a instituciones sociales’ (Cochabamba): B-3. Los Tiempos (2003) ‘Policía Boliviana, búnker del enriquecimiento’ (Cochabamba): B-2. Lustig, Nora (1995) Coping with Austerity: Poverty and Inequality in Latin America. Wash- ington, DC: Brookings Institution. Medeiros, Carmen (2001) ‘Civilizing the Popular? The Law of Popular Participation and the Design of a New Civil Society in 1990s Bolivia’, Critique of Anthropology 21(4): 401–25. Méndez, Juan E., Guillermo O’Donnell and Paulo Sérgio Pinheiro (eds) (1999) The (Un)rule of Law and the Underprivileged in Latin America. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. Merry, Sally Engle (1981) Urban Danger: Life in a Neighborhood of Strangers. Phila- delphia, PA: Temple University Press. Merry, Sally Engle (2001) ‘Spatial Governmentality and the New Urban Social Order: Controlling Gender Violence through Law’, American Anthropologist 103(1): 16–29. Ong, Aihwa (1999) Flexible Citizenship: The Cultural Logics of Transnationality. Durham, NC and London: Duke University Press. Opinión (2002) ‘Los linchamientos se repiten porque las autoridades no hacen nada para evitarlos’ (Cochabamba) 21 June: A1. Opinión (2003a) ‘Bolivia ocupa el segundo lugar en el mundo en casos de linchamientos’ (Cochabamba) 14 July: 4A. Opinión (2003b) ‘El linchamiento tiene hermanas siamesas: La pobreza y violencia’ (Cochabamba) 15 July: 10–11A. Opinión (2003c) ‘Tensa calma y total parálisis en ciudades de La Paz y El Alto’, (Cochabamba) 17 July: A1. Pereira, Anthony W. and Diane E. Davis (2000) ‘Introduction: New Patterns of 410 Critique of Anthropology 25(4) © 2005 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 10, 2008 http://coa.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://coa.sagepub.com Militarized Violence and Coercion in the Americas’, Latin American Perspectives 27(2): 3–17. Petras, James and Henry Veltmeyer (1999) ‘Latin America at the End of the Millen- nium’, Monthly Review 51(3): 31–52. Postero, Nancy (1999) ‘Bolivia’s Indígena Citizen: Multiculturalism in a Neoliberal Age’, paper presented at the meetings of the American Anthropological Associ- ation, 17–21 November, Chicago, IL. Radcliffe, Sarah A. and Sallie Westwood (1996) Remaking the Nation: Place, Identity, and Politics in Latin America. London: Routledge. Rhyne, Elisabeth (2001) Mainstreaming Microfinance: How Lending to the Poor Began, Grew, and Came of Age in Bolivia. Bloomfield, CT: Kumarian. Robinson, William (2004) A Theory of Global Capitalism: Production, Class and State in a Transnational World. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press. Rotker, Susana (ed.) (2002) Citizens of Fear: Urban Violence in Latin America. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press. Schneider, Cathy and Paul E. Amar (2003) ‘The Rise of Crime, Disorder and Authori- tarian Policing: An Introductory Essay’, NACLA Report on the Americas 37(2): 12–16. Schneider, Jane C. and Peter T. Schneider (2003) Reversible Destiny: Mafia, Antimafia, and the Struggle for Palermo. Berkeley: University of California Press. Solares Serrano, Humberto (1986) ‘Movimientos urbanos en Cochabamba’, Opinion (Cochabamba) 23 May: 5–6. Speed, Shannon and Alvaro Reyes (2002) ‘“In Our Own Defense”: Rights and Resist- ance in Chiapas’, Political and Legal Anthropology Review 25(1): 69–89. Ungar, Mark (2002) Elusive Reform: Democracy and the Rule of Law in Latin America. Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner. Ungar, Mark (2003) ‘Contested Battlefields: Policing in Caracas and La Paz’, NACLA Report on the Americas 37(2): 30–36. Urquidi Zambrana, Jorge (1967) La urbanización de la ciudad de Cochabamba: Síntesis del estudio. Antecedentes. Primera Parte. Cochabamba: Editorial Universitaria. Urquidi Zambrana, Jorge (1986) La urbanización de la ciudad de Cochabamba y el desarrollo regional y urbano: Examen crítico, Vol. 2. Cochabamba: Colegio de arquitectos de Bolivia, Filial Cochabamba. Vilas, Carlos M. (2001) ‘(In)justicia por mano propia: Linchamientos en el México contemporáneo’, Revista Mexicana de Sociología 63(1): 131–60. Weismantel, Mary (2001) Cholas and Pishtacos: Stories of Race and Sex in the Andes. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Williams, Raymond (1977) Marxism and Literature. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ■ Daniel M. Goldstein is Assistant Professor of Anthropology at Rutgers University. He received his PhD from the University of Arizona in 1997. With funding from a National Science Foundation research grant, he is currently investigating the relationship between personal insecurity and people’s attitudes about democratic governance in the marginal neighborhoods of Cochabamba. His book The Spec- tacular City: Violence and Performance in Urban Bolivia was published in 2004 by Duke University Press. Address: Department of Anthropology, Ruth Adams Building, 131 George Street, Rutgers University, New Brunswick, NJ 08901–1414, USA. [email: dgoldstein@anthropology.rutgers.edu] 411 Goldstein: Flexible Justice: Neoliberal Violence in Bolivia © 2005 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. at PENNSYLVANIA STATE UNIV on April 10, 2008 http://coa.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://coa.sagepub.com work_cv3xs4vdazeithyxrvd4tifuoa ---- Tilburg University Victim-centred restorative justice van Dijk, J.J.M. Published in: Restorative Justice Publication date: 2013 Document Version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): van Dijk, J. J. M. (2013). Victim-centred restorative justice. Restorative Justice, 1(3), 426-429. General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal ? Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 06. apr. 2021 https://research.tilburguniversity.edu/en/publications/cdf67976-a1a6-4b3c-b6b2-197e18d3a7cd NOTES FROM THE FIELD DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.5235/20504721.1.3.426 (2013) vol 1 issue 3Restorative Justice: An International Journal426 Victim-centred restorative justice Jan van Dijk Professor in Victimology, INTERVICT, Tilburg University (The Netherlands), Jan.vanDijk@uvt.nl. In the 1985 Council of Europe (CoE) Recommendation on the Position of the Victim in the Framework of Criminal Law and Procedure, one of the earliest European legal instru- ments on victims’ rights, mechanisms that are currently known as restorative justice (RJ) were not included in the primary recommendations but listed under a secondary, tamely framed recommendation ‘to examine the possible advantages of mediation and concili- ation schemes’. In the same year, the General Assembly of the United Nations adopted the UN Victims Declaration, Article 7 of which exhorts member states to utilise informal mechanisms ‘where appropriate to facilitate conciliation and redress for victims’. This is one of the subjects about which European victimologists were at the time more cau- tious than those experts from other regions, notably North America, who elaborated the draft of the Victims Declaration in Milan at the UN Crime Congress. The other area where diverging views surfaced was the right to express views and concerns in criminal proceedings, which found its way into the UN Declaration despite opposition and a formal reservation from the UK. Such a recommendation was nowhere to be seen in the CoE Recommendation of the same year. Clearly American and Canadian opinions in Milan prevailed over the European reservations that dominated the deliberations in Strasbourg.1 Since then the position of mediation, or RJ as it is now called in relevant legal instru- ments, has evolved. In 2000 the Economic and Social Council (ECOSOC) of the UN took note of the Basic Principles on the Use of Restorative Justice Programmes in Crimi- nal Matters. This legal text no longer refers to the concept of reconciliation but is in other respects more ambitious than the previous one in the UN Victims Declaration. It states that RJ ‘should be generally available at all stages of the criminal justice process’. However, two years later the ECOSOC took note of a revised text which states that RJ ‘may be used at any stage of the criminal justice process, subject to national law’. However the verb 1 The author was a member of the ad hoc committee elaborating the 1985 CoE Recommendation and took part in the debate in Milan at the UN Crime Congress as a member of the Dutch delegation. (2013) vol 1 issue 3 Restorative Justice: An International Journal 427 Victim-centred restorative justice ‘should’ should have been preferred to the auxiliary verb ‘may’. This change suggests that political support for RJ had lost some of its momentum on the global stage around 2000. In this regard it should also be highlighted that the two texts on RJ were adopted not by the General Assembly but by the considerably less authoritative ECOSOC and that the language used—‘takes note’ of the document, rather than ‘adopts it’—shows a lack of political consensus. It suggests that at least some countries represented in ECOSOC were unwilling to adopt or even welcome the draft text. In the meantime, on the European stage, support for RJ had begun to grow. The Council of Europe adopted its Recommendation on Mediation in Penal Matters in 1999. In this recommendation it is stated that mediation in penal matters should be generally available and that to this end legislation and guidelines are required. The CoE Recom- mendation of 2006 on Victim Assistance duly refers to the 1999 Recommendation on Mediation in Penal Matters. However, the EU Framework Decision of 2001 on the Standing of Victims in Criminal Proceedings is nuanced and less straightforward in its support of RJ. It states that member states ‘shall seek to promote mediation in criminal cases for offences which it considers appropriate for this sort of measure’. Here again one senses a turning of the tide around 2000. The belated European enthusiasm for RJ had apparently already waned somewhat. Considering this historical background, it comes as no surprise that in the long- awaited new EU Victims Directive (2012/29/EU) RJ is positioned as an option rather than as an obligation, and that the emphasis is on due process for victims. The provisions under review could in my view rightly be characterised as a plea for victim-centred RJ, a label inspired by the new concept of victim-friendly victim–offender dialogues in the USA, replacing older concepts such as victim–offender reconciliation schemes. These ‘notes from the field’ give me the opportunity to reflect on my own evolv- ing ideas on these matters over the past three decades. In the mid-1980s, as chair of the Dutch Victim Support Organisation, established in 1984, I was advocating easily accessi- ble victim support and better treatment of victims in criminal justice, including effective forms of compensation. These reformist ideas emanated from and were grounded in the idea that the welfare state should be expanded to reach out to crime victims. I was at the time sceptical about the victim’s right to speak up in court as advocated by American vic- timologists, and even more so of mediation, advocated in The Netherlands as a method to divert cases away from criminal justice, inter alia by abolitionists like Louk Hulsman and Herman Bianchi. I suspected those promoting RJ in The Netherlands of just paying lip service to the interests of victims and actually being more on the side of the offenders than of the victims. I was also suspicious of the situation in North America, where early RJ promoters advocated reconciliation and forgiveness as the aim of RJ rather than as one of its possible outcomes. Such supporters seemed to ignore the anger of victims and their search for vindication and compensation. In my view the development of victim support organisations and victim-centred reforms of the criminal justice system should (2013) vol 1 issue 3Restorative Justice: An International Journal428 Jan van Dijk be the first priorities of the victims movement and I regarded RJ as a distraction and, possibly, even a trap for victims. In my experience, victims themselves rarely asked to have their cases diverted away from criminal justice. They tend to ask for better treat- ment by the system, or in other words, for victim-friendly reforms of the system and not for an alternative system. In the meantime two factors have influenced my views of the role of victims in for- mal or informal proceedings, including RJ. The first is that increasing empirical evidence has been presented that participation in both criminal trials and RJ programmes can indeed benefit victims. Secondly, much progress has since been made with the empower- ment of victims through victim support and better treatment within criminal procedure. The victim has been put in a stronger social and legal position and this has undeniably increased his/her agency and freedom to act effectively as a party in proceedings. In the current situation in The Netherlands, for example, victims of serious crimes can rely on support from a case manager of Victim Support Netherlands and from a legal counsel paid for by the state. They also have their own seat in the courtroom. In this new context, I think the right of victims to speak up in court and present their views is now to be wel- comed as an option for those victims who feel ready for it. I am now also more positive towards RJ mechanisms as an option for victims who feel ready for it than I was 30 years ago. My fears that victims would be manipulated and possibly mistreated in the course of RJ procedures by overzealous mediators have diminished because of the improved cultural environment for victims. Victims seem to me now to be sufficiently empowered to take part in RJ procedures without the risk of secondary victimisation. Considering these changes, I now welcome the plea for victim-friendly RJ in the new Directive. I also agree with the criticism that the text is disappointingly weak on the right of victims to benefit from RJ when they opt for such a procedure. The right of voice in the trial to some extent allows the victim the right to confront his/her offender but this is and will remain an option in only a minority of cases. Many less serious cases are never brought before the court. It is a great breakthrough that victims should, according to the Directive, have the right to appeal a decision not to prosecute. This may in fact prove to be the most revolutionary element of the Directive. However, I would also like to give victims the right to access an RJ programme in such cases as an option. In other words, if the prosecutor drops the case for reasons of expediency, the victim should have the right to request a RJ programme instead, besides having the right to appeal against the dismissal. This is an important right in view of the increasing tendency of prosecutors in many European countries to enter into forms of plea bargaining with the suspect in order to speed up the proceedings. These forms of plea bargaining are likely to under- mine the newly gained participatory rights of the victims and this negative effect could in part be counter-balanced by participation in RJ programmes. Finally, I would also want to argue in favour of the right of victims of serious crimes to arrange a meeting with the offender after his/her conviction. To my knowledge such meetings are desired (2013) vol 1 issue 3 Restorative Justice: An International Journal 429 Victim-centred restorative justice by a good many victims for a variety of reasons—certainly not always a desire for recon- ciliation but also to confront the offender with the consequences of his/her crime or to ask for an explanation. In my opinion, the satisfaction of this legitimate need of victims ought to be facilitated by the state. To conclude, I agree with Katrien Lauwaert that the time has come to acknowledge access to victim-friendly RJ as a victim’s right at all relevant stages of the proceedings. In this respect the Directive, however welcome otherwise, falls short of expectations. Regarding RJ the European Commission seems to have erred on the side of caution. work_cvvjrfo72rdwbppjra65skx36a ---- 108 Book reviews Equal Justice Eric Rakowski, 385 +xii pages, Oxford, 1991, Clarendon Press, £40.00. Professor Rakowski begins his book with a quote from Aristotle's Politics: 'All hold that justice is some kind of equality'. His own account of an egalitarian conception of distributive justice in this outstanding book ranks alongside the pioneering work recently done in this area by writers such as John Rawls and Ronald Dworkin. Rakowski's answer to the question of how scarce resources are to be shared around he calls 'equality of fortune', and his defence of this notion takes up the first half of the book. Like G A Cohen, Rakowski believes that the essence of egalitarianism lies in evening out the effects of 'brute' bad luck, that is, ill fortune which is not the result of risk incurred by the agent. Inequalities arising from chance require a redistribution of resources, and 'resources' here include physical and mental capacities. Ideally, each should start life with equally valuable resources, subject to two caveats: there is some presumption in favour of allowing gifts and bequests to children; and great sacrifices cannot be called for from the more fortunate. Rakowski's is not merely a 'starting-gate' theory. Equality of fortune as a general ideal - along with a stress on the importance of personal autonomy - requires the establishment of various insurance schemes, and the details of these are developed carefully in the book. Theories of justice are often set in opposition to utilitarianism, and here Rakowski's thesis looks particularly strong: why should someone who has already been dealt a bad hand by fate suffer yet more at the hands of morality on the ground that he or she will be an inefficient consumer of resources? Like Rawls, Rakowski offers us a view of 'justice as fairness'. Rakowski closes Part I of the book with a chapter on whether transferable organs or blood should be seen as resources subject to redistribution. He argues that they should be, and that in certain circumstances compulsory extraction of, for example, blood might be justified. This would be unusual, however, if his recommendation that post mortem extractions be the norm were adopted. Part II of the book defends an account of strict liability which may be useful to those interested in medical negligence. In particular, Rakowski's attack on the idea that tort law is to be understood in wealth maximising terms is such that this view must henceforth be consigned to the dustbin of philosophical history. In Part III, Rakowski returns to the more straightforwardly medical ethical issue of the allocation of life-saving resources. He argues that numbers are relevant in life-saving decisions, but not because it is objectively better if, other things being equal, a larger group survives. Rather, we are each required now to form an intention to save the larger group in any such case, since this is in the interest of all. Rakowski dedicates a chapter to considering whether particular characteristics ofpersons, such as age or moral character, should influence choices between lives. His subtle discussion concludes that only (i) large differences in age and (ii) the individual's responsibility for his or her plight are relevant. He ends the book by defending a rights-based view against, in most circumstances, killing one being to benefit others. I disagree with some of Rakowski's negative arguments, acute as they are; but his sophisticated and humane account of justice is among the most powerful and persuasive I have read. His discussions of medical ethical questions will be the starting point for those who address these questions in future. This is a book that deserves to be - and no doubt will be - taken very seriously indeed. ROGER CRISP, Fellow in Philosophy, St Anne's College, Oxford. AIDS: an Epidemic of Ethical Puzzles Edited by the Hastings Center, USA, 187 pages, Dartmouth, 1991, Gower Academic Publishing Group, £32.50 hc. The acquired immune deficiency syndrome, with its undertones of sexuality and a pervasive fear of contagion, has been the catalyst for a revolution in professional ethics. The issues of patient autonomy, the conduct of placebo control trials, the rights of confidentiality, informed consent, death with dignity, and the obligations to provide care for individual health care workers are all explored in this recent collection of papers from the Hastings Center. What struck me most forcibly, on reading this book, was the major shift in ethical perceptions during the AIDS epidemic. The early paternalistic pronouncements from professional bodies have been modified in the light ofexperience and have lost some oftheir lofty tone. It is helpful in the present difficulties of the National Health Service to recognise that in Britain there has long been a consensus of an entitlement to health care by all and a less well expressed view of the obligation of individual health-care workers to provide such treatment. Such a consensus does not exist in the United States where health care is not freely available to all and professional bodies jealously cherish the right of doctors to act as independent contractors and to refuse to provide health care. Human immunodeficiency virus infection is slowly altering this perception with many States enacting anti-discriminatory legislation. The other fascinating aspect of this collection of papers is a thought- provoking review of the obligations and opportunities of researchers in the Third World. The changes in ethics occurring in different social and cultural situations are clearly expounded. As a lay reader I am always left vaguely disappointed that this sort of book does not provide a few simple rules which would guide me in day-to- day ethical decisions. I am, however, reassured when I discover that people who have made the study of ethics their lifetime's work face the same difficulties. This book is a fascinating historical account of the ethical dilemmas produced by the AIDS epidemic and makes a thought- provoking change from the average textbook, although it is rather expensive at £32. BRIAN GAZZARD, Consultant Physician and AIDS Co-ordinator, Westminster Hospital, Dean Ryle Street, Horseferry Road, London SWIP 2AP. Family Rights: Family Law and Medical Advance Edited by Elaine Sutherland and Alexander McCall Smith, 135 pages, Edinburgh, 1991, Edinburgh Press, £25.00. o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://jm e .b m j.co m / J M e d E th ics: first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /jm e .1 8 .2 .1 0 8 o n 1 Ju n e 1 9 9 2 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://jme.bmj.com/ work_cx3pcy3rcndyfbyt5tuyhtyhkm ---- Journal of Applied Psychology 2001, Vol. 86, No. 3, 425-445 Copyright 2001 by the American Psychological Association, Inc. 0021-9010A)1/$5.00 DOI: 10.1037//0021-9010.86.3.425 Justice at the Millennium: A Meta-Analytic Review of 25 Years of Organizational Justice Research Jason A. Colquitt University of Florida Donald E. Conlon Michigan State University Michael J. Wesson and Christopher O. L. H. Porter Texas A&M University K. Yee Ng Michigan State University The field of organizational justice continues to be marked by several important research questions, including the size of relationships among justice dimensions, the relative importance of different justice criteria, and the unique effects of justice dimensions on key outcomes. To address such questions, the authors conducted a meta-analytic review of 183 justice studies. The results suggest that although different justice dimensions are moderately to highly related, they contribute incremental variance explained in fairness perceptions. The results also illustrate the overall and unique relationships among distributive, procedural, interpersonal, and informational justice and several organizational outcomes (e.g., job satisfaction, organizational commitment, evaluation of authority, organizational citizenship behavior, withdrawal, performance). These findings are reviewed in terms of their implications for future research on organizational justice. The study of justice or fairness has been a topic of philosophical interest that extends back at least as far as Plato and Socrates (Ryan, 1993). Colloquially, the term justice is used to connote "oughtness" or "righteousness." Under the purview of ethics, an act can be defined as just through comparison with a prevailing philosophical system. Unfortunately, often there is no agreement on what that philosophical system should be. For example, Aris- totle (reprinted in Frost, 1972) noted that people in different roles will advocate different justice rules, arguing that "the democrats are for freedom, oligarchs for wealth, others for nobleness of birth" (p. 136; see also Pillutla & Murnighan, 1999). In research in the organizational sciences, justice is considered to be socially constructed. That is, an act is defined as just if most individuals perceive it to be so on the basis of empirical research (Cropanzano & Greenberg, 1997). Thus, "what is fair" is derived from past research linking objective facets of decision making to subjective perceptions of fairness. In particular, justice in organi- zational settings can be described as focusing on the antecedents and consequences of two types of subjective perceptions: (a) the fairness of outcome distributions or allocations and (b) the fairness of the procedures used to determine outcome distributions or allocations. These forms of justice are typically referred to as Jason A. Colquitt, Department of Management, University of Florida; Donald E. Conlon and K. Yee Ng, Department of Management, Michigan State University, Michael J. Wesson and Christopher O. L. H. Porter, Department of Management, Texas A&M University. We thank George Barnekov and Yumi Eto for their assistance in gathering the articles covered in this review. Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to Jason A. Colquitt, Warrington College of Business Administration, Department of Management, University of Florida, P.O. Box 117165, Gainesville, Florida 32611-7165. Electronic mail may be sent to colquitt@ufl.edu. distributive justice (Adams, 1965; Deutsch, 1975; Homans, 1961; Leventhal, 1976) and procedural justice (Leventhal, 1980; Lev- enthal, Karuza, & Fry, 1980; Thibaut & Walker, 1975). Efforts to explain the impact of justice on effective organiza- tional functioning have come under the rubric of organizational justice research (Greenberg, 1987b, 1990b). Greenberg (1990b) described organizational justice as a literature "grown around attempts to describe and explain the role of fairness as a consid- eration in the workplace" (p. 400). This literature includes both field and laboratory research, and organizational justice has been among the most frequently researched topics in industrial- organizational psychology, human resource management, and or- ganizational behavior over the last decade (Cropanzano & Green- berg, 1997). As interest in organizational justice has proliferated, so too have the theoretical approaches used to study it, particularly in relation to procedural justice. These approaches each propose a different way of conceptualizing justice, from the provision of process control (Thibaut & Walker, 1975)' to a focus on consistency (Leventhal, 1980; Leventhal et al., 1980) and an examination of interpersonal treatment (Bies & Moag, 1986). In addition, a large number of studies have sought to link justice perceptions to a variety of organizational outcomes, including job satisfaction, or- ganizational commitment, withdrawal, and organizational citizen- ship behavior. Because of this diversity in theoretical approach and construct focus, organizational justice is a field in need of integration. There have been a number of narrative reviews that have sought to achieve such integration (e.g., Cropanzano & Greenberg, 1997; Folger & Cropanzano, 1998; Lind & Tyler, 1988; Greenberg, 1987b, 1990b). However, important questions remain, including the following: How highly related are the different dimensions of organizational justice, and can they be empirically distinguished 425 426 COLQUITT, CONLON, WESSON, PORTER, AND NG from one another? Have the different ways of conceptualizing justice improved our ability to create perceptions of fairness? and What are the relationships between different organizational justice dimensions and important outcomes relevant to organizations? The first question deals with issues of construct discrimination (i.e., to what extent are constructs distinct from one another?). The second question deals with what Greenberg (1987b) called proactive re- search (i.e., research devoted to creating perceptions of fairness). The last question deals with what Greenberg (1987b) called reac- tive research (i.e., research devoted to understanding how individ- uals react to fair or unfair treatment). The purpose of this study was to conduct a comprehensive, meta-analytic review of the existing literature on organizational justice. To our knowledge, a meta-analysis has never been con- ducted in the organizational justice literature, even though meta- analysis has several important strengths relative to traditional narrative reviews (Hunter & Schmidt, 1990). First, meta-analysis is a more powerful summarizing tool because it yields a quantita- tive population value for a relationship of interest. Second, meta- analysis typically includes more studies than narrative reviews and is therefore less susceptible to biases based on study inclusion. Third, meta-analysis allows the reviewer to understand why rela- tionships in the literature vary as a function of sampling error, measurement error, and moderator variables. These strengths make meta-analysis an effective way of examining the three types of questions just listed. We conducted meta-analyses on all articles in the organizational justice literature published since 1975. We chose 1975 as our starting date because this is when Thibaut and Walker introduced the procedural justice construct, which allowed for the compara- tive study of the influence of multiple dimensions of justice. That year also marks, approximately, the time when justice researchers began integrating fairness concerns with outcomes relevant to organizations (e.g., job satisfaction and organizational commit- ment). Thus, as we reach the millennium, this review covers a quarter century of academic research. Our analyses dealt with all three types of questions raised earlier: construct discrimination issues, proactive research issues, and reactive research issues. In total, we relied on 120 separate meta-analyses, along with the emerging technique of meta-analytic regression analysis (Viswes- varan & Ones, 1995), to explore the three types of questions. We provide a brief review of the organizational justice literature before reviewing the specific research questions explored in this article. A Brief Review of the Organizational Justice Literature Introduction of Distributive Justice Before 1975, the study of justice was primarily concerned with distributive justice. Much of this research was derived from initial work conducted by Adams (1965), who used a social exchange theory framework to evaluate fairness. According to Adams, what people were concerned about was not the absolute level of out- comes per se but whether those outcomes were fair. Adams sug- gested that one way to determine whether an outcome was fair was to calculate the ratio of one's contributions or "inputs" (e.g., education, intelligence, and experience) to one's outcome and then compare that ratio with that of a comparison other. Although the comparison of the two input-outcome ratios gives Adams's equity theory an "objective" component, he was clear that this process was completely subjective. Whereas Adams's theory advocated the use of an equity rule to determine fairness, several other allocation rules have also been identified, such as equality and need (e.g., Leventhal, 1976). Studies have shown that different contexts (e.g., work vs. family), different organizational goals (e.g., group harmony vs. productiv- ity), and different personal motives (e.g., self-interest motives vs. altruistic motives) can activate the use or primacy of certain allocation rules (Deutsch, 1975). Nevertheless, all of the allocation standards have as their goal the achievement of distributive justice; they merely attempt to create it through the use of different rules. Introduction of Procedural Justice With the publication of their book summarizing disputant reac- tions to legal procedures, Thibaut and Walker (1975) introduced the study of process to the literature on justice. Thibaut and Walker (1975) viewed third-party dispute resolution procedures such as mediation and arbitration as having both a process stage and a decision stage. They referred to the amount of influence disputants had in each stage as evidence of process control and decision control, respectively. Their research suggested that disputants were willing to give up control in the decision stage as long as they retained control in the process stage. Stated differently, disputants viewed the procedure as fair if they perceived that they had process control (i.e., control over the presentation of their arguments and sufficient time to present their case). This process control effect is often referred to as the "fair process effect" or "voice" effect (e.g., Folger, 1977; Lind & Tyler, 1988), and it is one of the most replicated findings in the justice literature. Indeed, Thibaut and Walker (1975) virtually equated process control with procedural justice (Folger & Cropanzano, 1998). Although Thibaut and Walker (1975) introduced the concept of procedural justice, their work focused primarily on disputant re- actions to legal procedures. Although a focus on justice and law continues to be of interest to scholars (e.g., Tyler, 1990), Leventhal and colleagues can be credited for extending the notion of proce- dural justice into nonlegal contexts such as organizational settings (Leventhal, 1980; Leventhal et al., 1980). In doing so, Leventhal and colleagues also broadened the list of determinants of proce- dural justice far beyond the concept of process control. Leventhal's theory of procedural justice judgments focused on six criteria that a procedure should meet if it is to be perceived as fair. Procedures should (a) be applied consistently across people and across time, (b) be free from bias (e.g., ensuring that a third party has no vested interest in a particular settlement), (c) ensure that accurate infor- mation is collected and used in making decisions, (d) have some mechanism to correct flawed or inaccurate decisions, (e) conform to personal or prevailing standards of ethics or morality, and (f) ensure that the opinions of various groups affected by the decision have been taken into account. Introduction of Interactional Justice Bies and Moag (1986) introduced the most recent advance in the justice literature by focusing attention on the importance of the quality of the interpersonal treatment people receive when proce- dures are implemented. Bies and Moag (1986) referred to these META-ANALYTIC REVIEW OF ORGANIZATIONAL JUSTICE 427 aspects of justice as "interactional justice." More recently, inter- actional justice has come to be seen as consisting of two specific types of interpersonal treatment (e.g., Greenberg, 1990a, 1993b). The first, labeled interpersonal justice, reflects the degree to which people are treated with politeness, dignity, and respect by author- ities or third parties involved in executing procedures or determin- ing outcomes. The second, labeled informational justice, focuses on the explanations provided to people that convey information about why procedures were used in a certain way or why outcomes were distributed in a certain fashion. Questions Permeating the Organizational Justice Literature The proliferation of studies on organizational justice has cer- tainly enhanced the visibility of fairness concerns, but the large number of studies and the differing theoretical perspectives raise the concern that justice scholars may be "losing the forest for the trees." In other words, despite the large accumulation of findings, many central questions remain either unaddressed or unclear. Until such questions are addressed, theory development in the organi- zational justice literature will continue to be hindered. Our meta- analytic review examines some of these central questions, with specific areas of focus discussed in the sections to follow. Construct Discrimination Questions Perhaps the oldest debate in the justice literature concerns the independence of procedural and distributive justice. Some studies have revealed extremely high correlations between the two justice dimensions, suggesting that they may not be distinct in the minds of many people (Folger, 1987). For example, Sweeney and Mc- Farlin (1997) found an uncorrected correlation of .72 between procedural and distributive justice in a study of attitudes among federal employees. Welbourne, Balkin, and Gomez-Mejia (1995) found an uncorrected correlation of .74 in a study of employees in two different companies, one a high-technology firm and the other a consumer products firm. Possibly as a result of such findings, Martocchio and Judge (1995) conducted a study of disciplinary decisions in which no effort was made to separate procedural and distributive justice. Rather, the authors examined the effects of "organizational justice." Such high correlations are congruent with theoretical arguments made by Cropanzano and Ambrose (2001). These authors have argued that the procedural justice-distributive justice distinction, although necessary and valuable, may sometimes be overempha- sized. Their "monistic perspective" notes that procedural evalua- tions are based in large part on outcomes attained (Thibaut & Walker, 1975) and that the same event can be seen as a process in one context and an outcome in another. For example, reorganizing a performance evaluation system so that it provides employees more process control can be termed a fair outcome, even though process control is a procedural construct. The construct discrimination concern applies to an even greater degree to procedural and interactional justice. Bies and Moag (1986) originally declared interactional justice to be a third type of justice. They argued that people draw on interactional justice perceptions when deciding how to react to authority figures (i.e., bosses and supervisors), whereas procedural justice perceptions are used to decide how to react to the overall organization. How- ever, Bies retracted the position that interactional justice was a third type of justice in a subsequent review (Tyler & Bies, 1990). The author's retraction of his earlier stance has become widely held, as one recent narrative review treated interactional justice as a social form of procedural justice (Cropanzano & Greenberg, 1997). In keeping with this view, many researchers have opera- tionalized procedural justice by measuring process control or Lev- enthal criteria, along with interactional justice, in one combined scale (e.g., Brockner, Siegel, Daly, & Martin, 1997; Brockner, Wiesenfeld, & Martin, 1995; Folger & Konovsky, 1989; Konovsky & Folger, 1991; Mansour-Cole & Scott, 1998; Skarlicki & Latham, 1997). This practice seems to suggest that the inter- personal implementation of procedures need not (or cannot) be separated from their structural aspects. However, other research has renewed the debate surrounding the distinctiveness of procedural and interactional justice. Studies that have examined the two constructs separately have shown that they have different correlates or independent effects, or both (e.g., Barling & Phillips, 1993; Blader & Tyler, 2000; Cropanzano & Prehar, 1999; Masterson, Lewis, Goldman, & Taylor, 2000; Moye, Masterson, & Bartol, 1997; Skarlicki & Folger, 1997). Blader and Tyler (2000), in a survey of 404 U.S. workers, found that system- originating procedural factors and leader-originating procedural factors remained distinct in a confirmatory factor analysis. Master- son, Lewis, et al. (2000) drew on social exchange theory to show that procedural and interactional justice affected other variables through different intervening mechanisms. Specifically, proce- dural justice affected other variables by altering perceived organi- zational support perceptions; interactional justice affected other variables by altering leader-member exchange perceptions (Graen & Scandura, 1987). Even assuming that interactional justice can and should be distinguished from procedural justice, another question is whether the interpersonal and informational facets of the construct merit conceptual separation. Greenberg (1993b) suggested that interper- sonal and informational justice should be separated because they are logically distinct and have been shown to have independent effects (e.g., Greenberg, 1993c, 1994). Interpersonal justice acts primarily to alter reactions to decision outcomes, because sensi- tivity can make people feel better about an unfavorable outcome. Informational justice acts primarily to alter reactions to proce- dures, in that explanations provide the information needed to evaluate structural aspects of the process. Some recent work has attempted to address the construct dis- crimination questions raised earlier. Colquitt (2001) developed measures of distributive, procedural, informational, and interper- sonal justice based on the seminal introductions of each construct (Bies & Moag, 1986; Leventhal, 1976, 1980; Leventhal et al., 1980; Thibaut & Walker, 1975) and validated them in both a university and a field setting. Colquitt found that a four-factor confirmatory model provided the best fit to the data and further showed that the four justice dimensions predicted different out- comes. Thus, although some progress is being made, the literature on organizational justice is still marked by a debate over whether the domain includes one, two, three, or four dimensions of justice. This is the subject of the first research question addressed in our meta-analytic review. 428 COLQUITT, CONLON, WESSON, PORTER, AND NG Research Question 1: How highly related are the different dimensions of organizational justice, and can they be empirically distinguished from one another? Proactive Research Questions The history of research devoted to understanding what promotes perceptions of fairness has been marked by increasing complexity in operationalization as new and different conceptualizations have been introduced over the years. Thibaut and Walker (1975) ini- tially assumed that perceptions of procedural fairness were driven by process control. Leventhal and colleagues (Leventhal, 1980; Leventhal et al., 1980), on the other hand, eschewed the parsimo- nious approach offered by Thibaut and Walker and instead argued that fairness perceptions were created by adherence to six different criteria. Bies and Moag (1986) further suggested that fairness perceptions were created by the proper enactment of procedures in terms of interpersonal and informational justice. Such additional complexity is warranted if new approaches contribute incrementally to our understanding of how to foster perceptions of procedural fairness. Unfortunately, at present we do not actually know whether such incremental contributions exist. This is because so many studies of procedural justice collapse process control, Leventhal criteria, and interpersonal and informa- tional justice into a single variable (e.g., Brockner et al., 1995, 1997; Folger & Konovsky, 1989; Konovsky & Folger, 1991; Mansour-Cole & Scott, 1998; Skarlicki & Latham, 1997). This makes it impossible to gauge the relative influence of each element on procedural fairness perceptions. Still other studies assess only one conceptualization of procedural justice, again making it im- possible to assess the merits of different approaches. Moreover, it is well accepted that people judge procedures as more fair when they result in fair or favorable outcomes (Lind & Tyler, 1988; Thibaut & Walker, 1975). Despite this, many studies of procedural justice do not also examine distributive justice. Other studies do examine distributive justice but use it only in analyses separate from procedural justice. As a result, we cannot even be sure that process control, Leventhal criteria, and so forth explain variance in procedural fairness perceptions beyond distributive justice. If the operationalizations of procedural justice contribute little to procedural fairness perceptions beyond simple outcome fairness, then the focus on additional conceptualizations has been unwarranted. Thus, in terms of creating procedural fairness perceptions, it is unclear to what extent new conceptualizations of procedural jus- tice (including the relatively recent introductions of interpersonal and informational justice) have contributed to our understanding. Nor is it clear how important they are beyond the fairness of outcome distributions. This is the subject of our next two research questions. Research Question 2: Have the additional conceptualizations of pro- cedural justice developed over time (including interpersonal and in- formational justice) contributed incremental variance explained in procedural fairness perceptions? Research Question 3: Do those conceptualizations contribute incre- mental variance explained in procedural fairness perceptions beyond the effects of distributive justice? Reactive Research Questions Of course, one of the reasons scholars study justice is the belief that enhanced fairness perceptions can improve outcomes relevant to organizations (e.g., organizational commitment, job satisfaction, and performance). One goal of our meta-analytic review is to help develop some consensus regarding the relationships between di- mensions of justice and key outcomes. In particular, we evaluate the predictive ability of three different models that attempt to explain relationships between justice dimensions and important outcomes. These three models are the distributive dominance model suggested by Leventhal (1980), the two-factor model sug- gested by Sweeney and McFarlin (1993), and the agent-system model suggested by Bies and Moag (1986). The relative predictive power of procedural and distributive justice has been of long-standing concern in the justice literature. An interesting aspect of Leventhal's (1980) work is that he ex- plicitly considered the impact of both procedural and distributive justice and argued that distributive justice is generally more salient than procedural justice. He further argued that distributive justice judgments are likely to be more influential than procedural justice judgments in determining "overall fairness judgments" (Leventhal, 1980, p. 133; Lind & Tyler, 1988). Consistent with this argument, Conlon (1993) found that distributive justice explained more vari- ance in grievant evaluations of authorities (an appeal board) than did procedural justice. These works support a strong, parsimonious prediction that distributive justice will dominate (i.e., explain more variance than) other forms of justice. However, some prior research and theory have questioned this thesis. In perhaps the first empirical study to explicitly link mul- tiple dimensions of justice to organizational outcomes, Alexander and Ruderman (1987) surveyed more than 2,000 federal employ- ees, measuring procedural and distributive justice along with six outcomes. Their regression analyses showed that justice measures affected five of six organizational outcomes and that, for four of these five outcomes, procedural justice had stronger relationships than distributive justice. More recently, scholars have argued that distributive justice is likely to exert greater influence on more specific, person- referenced outcomes such as satisfaction with a pay raise or performance evaluation. In contrast, procedural justice is likely to exert greater influence on more general evaluations of systems and authorities (Greenberg, 1990b; Lind & Tyler, 1988). Consistent with this prediction, McFarlin and Sweeney (1992) found that distributive justice was a more important predictor of what they termed two "personal outcomes" (pay satisfaction and job satis- faction) and that procedural justice was a more important predictor of two "organizational outcomes" (organizational commitment and subordinate's evaluation of supervisor). Sweeney and McFarlin (1993) conducted perhaps the most comprehensive test of this notion. They contrasted four models expressing the relationship between procedural and distributive justice and two outcomes (pay satisfaction and organizational commitment). The idea that procedural justice predicts more system-referenced outcomes and distributive justice predicts more person-referenced outcomes was termed in their article the "two- factor model." They found that the two-factor model fit their data better than three competing models. Thus, drawing on the results META-ANALYTIC REVIEW OF ORGANIZATIONAL JUSTICE 429 of these studies, we examine the two-factor model's prediction of differing effects for procedural and distributive justice. Finally, Bies and Moag's (1986) focus on interpersonal treat- ment suggests a third approach to explaining organizational out- comes, one that explicitly examines the role of interpersonal and informational justice in addition to procedural justice. Recall that Bies and Moag (1986) originally argued that individuals draw on interpersonal and informational justice perceptions when deciding how to react to authority figures (i.e., bosses and supervisors) and draw on procedural justice perceptions when deciding how to react to the overall organization. Building on this work, Masterson, Lewis, et al. (2000) drew on social exchange theory (Blau, 1964) and reasoned that individuals in organizations were involved in two types of exchange relationships: exchanges with their imme- diate supervisor and exchanges with the larger organization. In a field study, the authors showed that interactional justice predicted supervisor-referenced outcomes (e.g., citizenship behaviors di- rected at supervisor and supervisor rating of performance), whereas procedural justice predicted organization-referenced out- comes (e.g., citizenship behaviors directed at the organization and organizational commitment). Thus, our third reactive model, the agent-system model, reflects the assertion that interpersonal and informational justice will be more powerful predictors of agent- referenced outcomes than system-referenced outcomes. The distributive dominance model, the two-factor model, and the agent-system model are explored in the following set of research questions. Research Question 4: What are the relationships between distributive justice and important organizational outcomes? Research Question 5: What are the relationships between procedural justice and important organizational outcomes? Research Question 6: What are the relationships between interper- sonal and informational justice and important organizational outcomes? Research Question 7: If considered simultaneously, what are the unique effects of these justice dimensions on key outcomes, and which of the three reactive models receives the most support? Our review focuses on several different outcomes representing those most commonly examined in the organizational justice lit- erature. In the following sections, we briefly review each type of outcome. Outcome satisfaction. Many justice studies have measured satisfaction with the outcomes of a decision-making process, such as pay, promotions, and performance evaluations. Given the logic presented earlier, we expect that distributive justice judgments will be a better predictor of outcome satisfaction than will procedural justice or interpersonal and informational justice. This pattern has been empirically supported through the use of pay satisfaction and satisfaction with job restructuring (e.g., Folger & Konovsky, 1989; Lowe & Vodanovich, 1995; Sweeney & McFarlin, 1993), and it is consistent with both the distributive dominance and two-factor models. Job satisfaction. Many studies also ask about employees' sat- isfaction with their jobs in general. McFarlin and Sweeney (1992) showed that distributive justice was a more powerful predictor of job satisfaction than was procedural justice. However, this does not seem to fit the two-factor theory argument that procedural justice predicts system-referenced outcomes, whereas distributive justice predicts person-referenced outcomes. Job satisfaction is a more general, multifaceted, and global response than is outcome satisfaction. Consistent with this reasoning, other studies have shown high correlations between procedural justice and job satis- faction (e.g., Mossholder, Bennett, & Martin, 1998; Wesolowski & Mossholder, 1997). In addition, Masterson, Lewis, et al. (2000) showed procedural justice to be a stronger predictor of job satis- faction than interactional justice, although both had significant independent effects. These results are consistent with the two- factor model and the agent-system model. Organizational commitment. Organizational commitment rep- resents a global, systemic reaction that people have to the company for which they work. Most measures of organizational commit- ment assess affective commitment, the degree to which employees identify with the company and make the company's goals their own (Allen & Meyer, 1990). Prior work by Tyler (e.g., Tyler, 1990) argues that procedural justice has stronger relationships with support for institutions than does distributive justice. This is also consistent with the two-factor model and has been supported in several studies (e.g., Folger & Konovsky, 1989; McFarlin & Sweeney, 1992; Sweeney & McFarlin, 1993). However, we should note that several studies have instead supported the distributive dominance model. For example, Lowe and Vodanovich (1995) found a stronger relationship for distributive justice and organiza- tional commitment than for procedural justice, as did Greenberg (1994). Other results support the agent-system model, in which procedural justice is a stronger predictor of organizational com- mitment than interactional justice (Masterson, Lewis, et al., 2000). Trust. Trust has recently emerged as a popular topic in orga- nizational research (as evidenced by the 1998 Academy of Man- agement Review special issue devoted to the topic). Tyler (1989) argued that trust in decision makers or authorities is important because these people typically have considerable discretion in terms of allocating rewards and resources. Whereas Tyler (1989) initially conceptualized trust in relation to a third party or an authority, Folger and Cropanzano (1998) made the point that trust reactions are relevant to any person with whom one is interdepen- dent. Given the centrality of trust in theorizing on procedural justice, we would expect to find stronger relationships between trust and procedural justice than between trust and distributive justice, consistent with past research (e.g., Alexander & Ruder- man, 1987; Konovsky & Pugh, 1994). However, given that trust is usually referenced to a particular person, the agent-system model would predict that interpersonal and informational justice are even better predictors of this outcome than procedural justice. Evaluation of authority. A number of studies of third-party dispute resolution procedures have asked disputants to make eval- uations of the third party (Lind & Tyler, 1988). Still other work in organizations asks respondents to rate the acceptability of their supervisors or management in more general terms. Much of the research on evaluation of authorities comes from work merging psychology and political science (e.g., Tyler, 1990). Tyler's (1990) work, along with the two-factor model, would suggest that we should find stronger relationships between procedural justice and evaluation of authorities than between distributive justice and evaluation of authorities. However, as with organizational com- mitment, this prediction has been supported in multiple studies (e.g., Ball, Trevino, & Sims, 1993; McFarlin & Sweeney, 1992) 430 COLQUITT, CONLON, WESSON, PORTER, AND NG and refuted in multiple studies (e.g., Conlon, 1993; Taylor, Tracy, Renard, Harrison, & Carroll, 1995). In addition, the agent-system model would predict that interpersonal and informational justice are better predictors of evaluation of authority in cases in which the authority in question is one's leader as opposed to management in general. For this reason, our examination of the reactive models distinguishes between agent-referenced evaluations of authority (e.g., focusing on one's supervisor) and system-referenced evalu- ations of authority (e.g., focusing on management in general). Organizational citizenship behaviors (OCBs). Organ (1990) defined OCBs as behaviors that are discretionary and not explicitly rewarded but that can help improve organizational functioning. Organ (1990) posited that OCBs are driven largely by fairness perceptions. He suggested that people in organizations assume, at the outset, a social exchange relationship. This expectation con- tinues until unfairness is evidenced, at which time the relationship is reinterpreted as economic rather than social. Research on OCBs has repeatedly demonstrated stronger linkages between procedural justice and OCBs than between distributive justice and OCBs (Ball, Trevino, & Sims, 1994; Moorman, 1991). For example, Moorman (1991) reported that procedural justice influenced four of five OCB dimensions, whereas distributive justice failed to influence any dimensions. Skarlicki and Latham (1996) even showed that training supervisors on procedural justice principles was capable of improving OCB levels. To the extent that OCBs were measured in relation to supervisors rather than the organiza- tion as a whole, we would expect interpersonal and informational justice to be stronger predictors, consistent with the agent-system model and the results of Masterson, Lewis, et al. (2000). Thus, our examination of the reactive models distinguishes between agent- referenced OCBs and system-referenced OCBs. Following Wil- liams and Anderson (1991), we refer to the former as individual OCBs (OCBIs) and the latter as organization OCBs (OCBOs). Withdrawal. Behaviors and behavioral intentions such as ab- senteeism, turnover, and neglect are often subsumed under the heading of job withdrawal. Although withdrawal is a relatively common outcome in the justice literature, it has not been examined in the context of the two-factor model. Withdrawal can occur as a result of a thorough, reasoned evaluation of the organization as a system or on a more "spur of the moment" basis in reaction to an unsatisfactory outcome or poor interpersonal treatment by an au- thority. However, because employees who withdraw are typically leaving the overall organization, we would argue that withdrawal is system referenced in nature, similar to organizational commit- ment. Unfortunately, the literature linking different justice dimen- sions to withdrawal is somewhat muddied, with some studies showing that distributive justice influences job withdrawal (e.g., Horn, Griffeth, & Sellaro, 1984) and other studies revealing effects for procedural justice (e.g., Dailey & Kirk, 1992). Moreover, Masterson, Lewis, et al. (2000) showed that procedural justice had more of an impact on withdrawal than interactional justice. Thus, past research has, at various times, supported the distributive dominance model, the two-factor model, and the agent-system model. Negative reactions. Some recent justice research has looked at the relationship between perceived unfairness and a variety of negative reactions, such as employee theft (e.g., Greenberg, 1990a, 1993c) and organizational retaliatory behaviors (ORBs; Skarlicki & Folger, 1997; Skarlicki, Folger, & Tesluk, 1999). As with withdrawal, negative reactions have not been examined from the standpoint of the two-factor model. Whereas negative reactions can occur because of purely cognitive evaluations of the merits of the organization as a whole or as strong emotional reactions to one's own treatment, reactions such as theft and ORBs clearly damage the larger organizational system. However, Skarlicki and Folger (1997) found that ORBs had approximately equal correla- tions with distributive, procedural, and interactional justice, with interactional justice having the strongest unique effect. To the extent that ORBs are system-referenced outcomes, this provides little support for any of the three reactive models. Performance. Perhaps the most unclear of all relationships in the justice literature is the relationship between procedural justice and performance. For example, Barley and Lind (1987) found a relationship between procedural fairness judgments and perfor- mance in a laboratory study but not in a field study. Kanfer, Sawyer, Barley, and Lind (1987) found a negative correlation between procedural justice and performance. Keller and Dansereau (1995) found a moderately strong relationship between procedural justice and performance as measured by performance appraisal records. Other studies have linked distributive justice to perfor- mance, consistent with equity theory's predictions (e.g., Ball et al., 1994; Griffeth, Vecchio, & Logan, 1989). It is difficult to apply the logic of the agent-system and two-factor models to the prediction of performance. On the one hand, performance supports, and is often measured by, agents such as one's supervisor. For this reason, Masterson, Lewis, et al. (2000) predicted, and found, stronger interactional justice effects on performance, consistent with the agent-system model. On the other hand, performance reflects members' contributions to organizational goals (Borman, 1991), giving it a system-referenced character and suggesting that procedural justice should be its primary predictor. Different Operationalizations of Procedural Justice Of course, the relative strength of the correlations between the justice dimensions and the outcomes just described may depend on how procedural justice is operationalized. For example, some studies assess only process control but label it procedural justice (e.g., Joy & Witt, 1992). Others use a variable that is composed only of Leventhal criteria, labeling that procedural justice (e.g., Konovsky & Folger, 1991). Still others measure informational or interpersonal justice as the process variable (e.g., Greenberg, 1990a). Another common operationalization is measuring proce- dural fairness perceptions (e.g., Bies, Martin, & Brockner, 1993; Colquitt & Chertkoff, 1996; Gilliland, 1994), which is what Lind and Tyler (1988) labeled a direct measure (i.e., a measure that directly asks respondents "how fair" a procedure is). Finally, another common operationalization is an indirect combination measure (Lind & Tyler, 1988). Such a measure asks respondents about some combination of process control, Leventhal criteria, and interpersonal or informational justice, labeling that procedural justice (e.g., Brockner et al., 1995, 1997; Folger & Konovsky, 1989; Konovsky & Folger, 1991; Mansour-Cole & Scott, 1998; Skarlicki & Latham, 1997). Presumably, those who use such measures subscribe to the view that interpersonal and informa- tional justice are facets of procedural justice, as with process control or Leventhal criteria. META-ANALYTIC REVIEW OF ORGANIZATIONAL JUSTICE 431 Our examination of the relative strength of the correlations between the different dimensions of justice and the outcomes described uses the broadest conceptualization of procedural justice by combining all of its potential operationalizations. However, our review also presents analyses broken down by operationalization. One strength of meta-analysis is that it allows a researcher to examine the degree to which a relationship varies across a partic- ular moderator variable. Our review examines operationalization as a moderator variable, allowing us to see to what extent rela- tionships vary by how procedural justice is conceptualized. For instance, one might expect that procedural fairness perceptions will yield the highest relationships with organizational outcomes, in that fairness perceptions could be construed as the intervening mechanism linking process control, Leventhal criteria, and so forth to outcomes. Conversely, one might expect indirect combination measures to yield the highest relationships, because they capture more of the conceptual domain of organizational justice. Method We conducted a meta-analytic review of the literature on organizational justice to examine the questions discussed earlier. In the following sec- tions, we review the methods for this review. Literature Search We first performed a literature search of the PsycINFO database for the years 1975 to 1999. Our starting date coincided with the year in which Thibaut and Walker (1975) introduced the procedural justice construct. Given that a major goal of this review was to examine the relative impact of multiple dimensions of justice, articles published before 1975 would be less useful. Such articles were typically proactive distributive justice arti- cles that examined how individuals allocate rewards across different situ- ations and did not normally assess any of the outcomes examined in this review. Moreover, from a practical perspective, articles published before 1975 rarely reported the types of statistics included in a meta-analysis. We conducted our literature search using the following keywords: procedural fairness, procedural justice, distributive fairness, distributive justice, inter- actional justice, interpersonal treatment, and equity. In addition to the PsycINFO search, we conducted an author search of 10 of the most published authors in the organizational justice literature. Any article that included a relationship in the meta-analysis, whether it was a single justice-outcome relationship or a relationship between two dimensions of justice, was relevant. The search yielded 300 articles. Of these 300 articles, 76 did not include a relationship in the meta-analysis and were deemed not relevant. For example, Tyler, Lind, Ohbuchi, Sugawara, and Huo (1998) examined the effects of ''relational judgments" (an aggregate measure of procedural, interpersonal, and informational justice judgments) on the willingness of disputants to accept a third-party solution in a conflict resolution setting. Bazerman, Schroth, Shah, Diekmann, and Tenbrunsel (1994) examined the effects of justice on job search decisions. Such studies did not focus on one of the nine outcome variables included in our review or did not include a relationship between different dimensions of justice. Another 41 studies included a relationship in the meta-analysis but could not be coded because of the way in which the results were presented. Meta-analysis requires zero-order effect size information, whether in the form of correlations, F statistics, t statistics, or even means and standard deviations of a dependent variable across multiple experimental conditions. Articles that present only partial or semipartial unique, independent effects cannot be coded unless the independent variables are uncorrelated, as in most experiments in which conditions are manipulated orthogonal to one another. Several articles uncovered in our literature review could not be coded because they presented only multiple regression or structural equa- tion modeling results. Examples included several of Tyler's investigations of the "relational" or "group-value" model of justice (e.g., Tyler, 1989, 1994; Tyler, Degoey, & Smith, 1996). Other articles could not be coded because they presented incomplete results (e.g., only labeling F statistics in an analysis of variance as significant or not significant) or combined procedural and distributive justice into a larger justice variable (e.g., Martocchio & Judge, 1995). The final number of studies included in the review was 183. These studies are marked with an asterisk in the References section. We should note that this number included both laboratory studies and field studies; the term organizational justice in no way implies that the research must occur in a field setting but indicates only that the research must be relevant to the role of fairness in the workplace (Greenberg, 1990b). Meta-Analysis Strategy Meta-analysis is a technique that allows individual study results to be aggregated while correcting for various artifacts that can bias relationship estimates. Our meta-analyses were conducted with Hunter and Schmidt's (1990) procedures. Inputs into the meta-analyses included zero-order effect sizes in the form of correlations, along with sample sizes and reliability information. In instances in which articles reported statistics other than correlations (e.g., F statistics, / statistics, or means and standard devia- tions), results were transformed into correlations through the formulas provided by Hunter and Schmidt (1990). Because of the subjectivity and judgment calls inherent in meta-analytic efforts, all coding of meta-analytic data was performed by author dyads formed from the study's five authors. In cases in which a variable was assessed with multiple measures, we acted in accordance with Hunter and Schmidt's (1990) recommendations for conceptual replication (see pp. 451-463). Specifically, when multiple measures were highly correlated and seemed to each be construct valid, the correlations were averaged together (see Hunter & Schmidt, 1990, p. 457). Thus, one composite correlation was formed in lieu of multiple correla- tions, preventing a study that involved multiple measures from being "double counted." This technique improves both reliability and construct validity. We should also note that, when an article reported results from multiple independent samples, each correlation was included in the meta- analysis (see Hunter & Schmidt, 1990, pp. 463-466, for a discussion of these issues). Meta-analysis requires that each observed correlation from a given study be weighted by that study's sample size to provide a weighted mean estimate of the population correlation. The standard deviation of this estimate across the multiple studies is also computed. This variation is composed of true variation in the population value as well as variation due to artifacts such as sampling error and measurement error. To provide a more accurate estimate of each population correlation and its variability, our analyses corrected for both sampling error and unreliability. However, because reliability information was not always available, the method of artifact-distribution meta-analysis was used (Hunter & Schmidt, 1990). For those studies that did not report reliability information for any given variable, that variable's weighted mean reliability based on all other studies was used to correct for measurement error. Meta-analysis results typically include both uncorrected (/•) and cor- rected (rc) estimates of the population correlation. The latter are corrected for unreliability in both variables. Also reported are the 95% confidence intervals for each population correlation. Confidence intervals are gener- ated with the standard error of the weighted mean correlation. They reflect the "extent to which sampling error remains in the estimate of a mean effect size" and are applied to estimates that have not been corrected for artifacts (Whitener, 1990, p. 316). If a confidence interval does not include the value of zero, that population correlation is judged to be "statistically significant." Also presented is the standard deviation of the population correlation (SDrc). This provides an index of the variation in the corrected population 432 COLQUITT, CONLON, WESSON, PORTER, AND NG values across the studies in our sample. One indication that moderators may be present in a given relationship is the case in which artifacts such as unreliability fail to account for a substantial portion of the variance in correlations. Thus, the percentage of variance explained by artifacts (Vm) is also presented. Hunter and Schmidt (1990) have suggested that, if artifacts fail to account for 75% of the variance in the correlations, moderators probably exist. Mathieu and Zajac (1990) and Horn, Caranikas- Walker, Prussia, and Griffeth (1992) amended the 75% criterion to 60% in cases in which range restriction is not one of the artifacts that is corrected for. We should note that the 60% rule only implies the existence of a moderator; it does not indicate what variable is acting as the moderator. Identifying the actual moderator variable requires coding potential mod- erators and then performing subgroup analyses to determine whether the population correlations vary across the subgroup boundaries. In our review, this entailed determining whether the population correlations varied across different operationalizations of procedural justice. Meta-Analytic Regression Strategy Many questions cannot be answered by a matrix of meta-analyzed correlations. For example, do Leventhal's (1980) justice criteria explain variance in procedural fairness perceptions beyond the effects of Thibaut and Walker's (1975) process control construct? Do procedural, distribu- tive, interpersonal, and informational justice each have independent effects on organizational commitment? Such questions require multiple regression to assess independent, semipartial effects. Fortunately, recent advances in meta-analytic regression have allowed researchers to combine the benefits of meta-analysis with the strengths of regression procedures (see Viswes- varan & Ones, 1995). Meta-analytic regression has been used in contexts such as training motivation (Colquitt, LePine, & Noe, 2000), leadership (Podsakoff, MacKenzie, & Bommer, 1996), turnover (Horn et al., 1992), and job performance (Schmidt, Hunter, & Outerbridge, 1986). In practice, there are some decision points that researchers using meta- analytic regression will encounter (Viswesvaran & Ones, 1995). First, many researchers will conduct regressions on correlation matrices that vary in sample size. This raises the question of what sample size to use when computing the standard errors associated with the regression weights. Potential solutions include using the smallest cell sample size or using the mean sample size. We chose to use the harmonic mean of the correlation matrix sample sizes, as opposed to the arithmetic mean (consistent with Viswesvaran & Ones, 1995). The formula for the harmonic mean is [MliW, + \IN2 + • • • + I/Ay], where k refers to the number of study correlations and N refers to the sample sizes of the studies. An inspection of the formula shows that the harmonic mean gives much less weight to substantially large individual study sample sizes, so it is always more conservative than the arithmetic mean (Viswesvaran & Ones, 1995). Note, however, that the sample size issue is not very critical to the current meta-analytic review. This is because the sample sizes for almost all of the cells of the correlation matrices are in the thousands, making even small effect sizes statistically significant, no matter what sample size option is used. Second, researchers must choose whether to use maximum-likelihood estimation (the choice of Horn et al., 1992), ordinary least squares (the choice of Colquitt et al., 2000, Podsakoff et al., 1996, and Schmidt et al., 1986), or some other method. We elected to use ordinary least squares estimation, consistent with Colquitt et al. (2000), Podsakoff et al. (1996), and Schmidt et al. (1986). Ordinary least squares assumptions are less restrictive than maximum likelihood, which assumes multivariate normal- ity. Maximum-likelihood estimation is also less optimal in instances in which the data are in the form of correlations rather than covariances (Cudeck, 1989). Given that meta-analysis results in correlational data, we believed that ordinary least squares would be more appropriate. Results Construct Discrimination Questions Research Question 1 concerned the magnitude of the relation- ships among the various organizational justice conceptualizations. Table 1 shows the correlations among process control, Leventhal criteria, interpersonal justice, informational justice, distributive justice, and procedural fairness perceptions. Cohen and Cohen (1983) classified correlations as high, moderate, or weak according to unconnected r values of .50, .30, and .10, respectively. Thus, Table 1 shows high correlations among the justice conceptualiza- tions, but not so high that they seem to be multiple indicators of one underlying construct. Process control and Leventhal criteria, the two original operationalizations of procedural justice, were highly correlated with each other (r = .50, rc = .67) and with procedural fairness perceptions (r = .41, rc = .51 and r = .53, rc = .68, respectively). However, the relationship between Leventhal criteria and procedural fairness perceptions was significantly stronger than the relationship between process control and proce- dural fairness perceptions, as evidenced by the fact that the two correlations' confidence intervals did not overlap. Table 1 also shows the correlations among the interactional justice dimensions. Interpersonal justice was highly related to informational justice (r = .57, rc = .66), although again not so highly that the two necessarily seem to be indicators of the same underlying construct. Interpersonal justice and informational jus- tice were also highly correlated with procedural fairness percep- tions (r = .56, rc = .63 and r = .51, rc = .58, respectively). These relationships were similar in magnitude to the process control and Leventhal relationships, although the interpersonal justice- procedural fairness relationship was significantly stronger than the process control-procedural fairness relationship. Interestingly, the relationships between interpersonal and infor- mational justice and procedural fairness perceptions were not significantly stronger than the relationship between distributive justice and procedural fairness perceptions (r = .48, rc = .57). This suggests that interpersonal and informational justice should be considered to be distinct from procedural justice, just as the case with distributive justice. The uncorrected correlation of .48 for distributive justice and procedural fairness perceptions may seem surprisingly low, given the many empirical articles that have reported uncorrected relationships in the .60s and .70s. To take a closer look at this relationship, Table 2 shows relationships be- tween distributive justice and every possible conceptualization of procedural justice, including interpersonal and informational jus- tice, to explore whether operationalization moderates the proce- dural justice-distributive justice relationship. The top row of Ta- ble 2, labeled "Broadly defined procedural justice," shows the procedural justice-distributive relationship in which all potential operationalizations, shown in the remaining rows, are considered together. The final row contains the "indirect combination mea- sure" operationalization discussed previously. Recall that indirect combination measures are those that assess some combination of process control, interpersonal or informational justice, and Lev- enthal variables. They are labeled indirect because they do not directly ask "how fair" something is (see Lind & Tyler, 1988). Combining all operationalizations, broadly defined procedural justice was strongly related to distributive justice (r = .56, rc = .67). The high standard deviation of the population correlation META-ANALYTIC REVIEW OF ORGANIZATIONAL JUSTICE 433 o cS 2" t I?'? Q &• v.°> -̂v. u _, fS •? m ̂ S- '31 ̂d s^ ^^ *§m _^ ^̂ '̂ J ̂ d §^ ?>5 0 s ̂e.-* c n ce p tu a liz a tic o U oo ^ ̂^o "̂ VO r? 11 n vn •"0 in ̂ li EH 2 S g — i r-j co Co ^ sO SO sO oo' ^ r- in o" 00 sp CO so" ^t ON in CO (N in in CO CO o 1 cfl £ c in oT 0 CO' _^ CO r- fN CO* in CO co" p^ ^p ^ 5 5 s^ S £ 5 CO CO o (N n co P Co ̂ °t \c' co" ̂ O\ sO in in" c^ o CO OO sp 6^ co'O •̂ "̂ >n ro — ( »n in °° S K pf ro — . \o uo" ̂ CO — « .2 D OH — ' in 06 0 m (N oo sq 0? o\ CN" SO CN O 1 in" _^ fN in CO so CO oo" so "S tj go ^s tz ,o .2 CD •a T3 ra c 3 II vj S C ra 1 0 ^o C3 1 1 £ £ Q u II c1 cT .2 03 1C oo c .2 S S. a T3 O S CJ c a T3 C O i_ "c3 S c •s iC p: o II 0 c',o "St c CJ C O 0̂. o p. u n co rr e ct e d II 1 *2 S "t: aj •a 3 >> "O c "a. x c c C3 'S •s t C OJ o s. II I (LJ •3 ° 1 s c II c o rr e la tio n ; k c 'i o. a (SDrc = .23) and the low variance explained from artifacts (Vart = 2.74%) show that moderators exist in the broadly defined procedural justice-distributive justice relationship. Operational- ization explains some of that variation, in that the highest relation- ship was evident when an indirect combination measure was used (r = .63, rc = .17). Moreover, because their confidence intervals do not overlap, Table 2 shows that the indirect combination mea- sure relationship is significantly stronger than the more unidimen- sional justice measures: procedural fairness perceptions (r — .48, rc = .57), process control (r = .27, rc = .34), Leventhal criteria (r = .46, rt = .55), interpersonal justice (r = .38, rc = .42), and informational justice (r = .39, rc = .46). Proactive Research Questions Research Question 2 explored whether the additional conceptu- alizations of justice over the course of its history have contributed incremental variance explained in regard to promoting procedural fairness perceptions. This was tested by regressing procedural fairness perceptions onto the various justice operationalizations using hierarchical regression. Order of entry was based on histor- ical introduction, so the following steps were used: (a) Thibaut and Walker's (1975) process control operationalization, (b) Lev- enthal's (1980) justice criteria operationalization, and (c) Bies and Moag's (1986) interactional justice construct, broken down into interpersonal and informational justice (as in Greenberg, 1993b). The meta-analytic regression results are shown in Table 3. The original operationalization of procedural justice, process control, explained 26% of the variance in procedural fairness perceptions, with higher levels of process control producing more favorable fairness perceptions (j3 = .51). Leventhal criteria explained an additional 21% of the variance, with higher levels of his criteria also producing more favorable perceptions (|8 = .61). Interper- sonal and informational justice explained an additional 6% of the variance in fairness perceptions. That effect was due primarily to interpersonal justice (|3 = .29), although informational justice also had a significant effect (jS = .11). Research Question 3 asked how much variance the justice operationalizations explained in procedural fairness perceptions beyond the effects of distributive justice. This was tested by regressing procedural fairness perceptions onto the various justice operationalizations after controlling for distributive justice. These regression results are shown in Table 4. Distributive justice ex- plained 33% of the variance in procedural fairness perceptions, with higher levels of distributive justice being associated with more favorable fairness perceptions (ft = .57). The remaining justice operationalizations explained an incremental 24% of the variance. However, only two operationalizations had strong unique effects: Leventhal criteria (/3 = .30) and interpersonal justice (f3 = .26). Although statistically significant, the unique effects of pro- cess control (ft = .03) and informational justice (j3 = .07) were not practically significant. Reactive Research Questions Research Questions 4-6 explored the relationships between the organizational justice dimensions and several key outcome vari- ables. Table 5 presents the results for these research questions. Research Question 4 explored the relationships between distribu- 434 COLQUITT, CONLON, WESSON, PORTER, AND NG Table 2 Relationship Between Distributive and Procedural Justice Conceptualizations (Including Interpersonal and Informational Justice) Distributive justice Conceptualization Broadly defined procedural justice Procedural fairness perceptions Process control Leventhal criteria Interpersonal justice Informational justice Indirect combination measure r (95% CI) .56 (.52, .60) .48 (.41, .55) .27 (.22, .33) .46 (.38, .54) .38 (.26, .50) .39 (.32, .47) .63 (.59, .66) rc (SDrJ .67 (.23) .57 (.28) .34 (.13) .55 (.17) .42 (.20) .46 (.15) .77 (.14) *W 92 (42,576) 45(13,418) 23(5,137) 15 (4,743) 9 (3,496) 14 (3,807) 54(51,446) V«(%) 2.74 3.41 24.15 8.27 5.62 13.19 2.32 Note, r = uncorrected population correlation; CI = confidence interval around uncorrected population correlation; rc = corrected population correlation; SDrc = standard deviation of corrected population correlation; k = number of studies; Vart = percentage of variance in rc explained by study artifacts. live justice and the outcomes. Distributive justice had high corre- lations with outcome satisfaction (r = .52, rc = .61), job satisfac- tion (r = .46, rc = .56), organizational commitment (r — .42, rc = .51), trust (r = .48, rc = .57), agent-referenced evaluation of authority (r = .53, rc = .59), and withdrawal (r = -.41, rc = -.50). Distributive justice had moderate correlations with system- referenced evaluation of authority (r — .30, rc = .37), OCBOs (r = .20, rc = .25), and negative reactions (r = —.26, rc = —.30) and was weakly related to OCBIs (r = .13, rc = .15) and performance (r= .13, rc = .15). Research Question 5 explored relationships between procedural justice and the same set of outcomes. Combining all conceivable procedural justice conceptualizations, again labeled broadly de- fined procedural justice, we see that procedural justice had high correlations with outcome satisfaction (r = .40, rc = .48), job satisfaction (r = .51, rc = .62), organizational commitment (r = .48, rc = .57), trust (r = .52, rc = .61), and agent-referenced evaluation of authority (r = .56, rc = .64). Procedural justice had moderate correlations with system-referenced evaluation of au- thority (r = .35, rc = .42), OCBOs (r = .23, rc = .27), withdrawal (r = —.36, rc = —.46), negative reactions (r = —.27, rc = —.31), and performance (r = .30, rc = .36). Finally, procedural justice had weak correlations with OCBIs (r = . 19, rc = .22). Table 5 also shows that moderators were present in the procedural justice- outcome relationships, with the exception of the relationships with the OCB variables. Operationalization could be one potential mod- erator for several of the outcome variables, because the indirect Table 3 Incremental Effects of Justice Operationalizations on Procedural Fairness Perceptions Regression step 1 . Process control 2. Leventhal criteria 3. Interpersonal justice Informational justice Total R2 .26* .47* .53* A/?2 .26* .21* .06* ft .51* .61* .28* .11* Note. N = 4,165 (based on the harmonic mean sample size of the Table 1 cells used in this regression). *p < .05. combination measure was significantly more related to job satis- faction, organizational commitment, and withdrawal than was any other Operationalization. Research Question 6 explored relationships between interper- sonal and informational justice and the outcome variables. Inter- personal justice was strongly related to agent-referenced evalua- tion of authority (r = .57, rc = .62) and moderately related to job satisfaction (r = .31, rc = .35), system-referenced evaluation of authority (r = .20, rc = .23), OCBIs (r = .23, rc = .29), and negative reactions (r = —.30, rc = —.35). It was weakly related to outcome satisfaction (r = .19), organizational commitment (r = . 16, rc = .19), withdrawal (r = —.02, rc = —.02), and performance (r = .03, rc = .03). Informational justice was strongly related to trust (r = .43, rc = .51), agent-referenced evaluation of authority (r = .58, rc = .65), and system-referenced evaluation of authority (r = .42, rc = .47) and was moderately related to outcome satisfaction (r = .27, rc = .30), job satisfaction (r = .38, rc = .43), organizational commitment (r = .26, rc = .29), OCBIs (r = .21, rc = .26), withdrawal (r = —.21, rc = -.24), and negative reactions (r = - .29, rc = - .33). It was weakly related to OCBOs (r = .18) and performance (r = .11, rc = .13). Research Question 7 examined the unique effects of the justice dimensions on the outcome variables considered simultaneously. Table 6 presents beta weights derived from regressing each of the outcomes on all four justice dimensions simultaneously. The table also presents unique R2 values derived from a "usefulness analy- sis" in which the effects of one justice dimension were examined after controlling for the others. The table also presents the total variance explained in each outcome by the justice dimensions. Note that, in some cases, the interpersonal justice beta weights were reversed in sign from that dimension's correlations. This was due to the multicollmearity in some of the regressions. If hierar- chical regression had been used and interpersonal justice had been entered in a step before procedural and informational justice were entered, the signs of the beta weights would not have been reversed. The regression results in Table 6 allowed us to examine the adequacy of the distributive dominance, two-factor, and agent- system reactive models. Leventhal's (1980) distributive domi- nance model would predict higher unique effects for distribu- META-ANALYTIC REVIEW OF ORGANIZATIONAL JUSTICE 435 Table 4 Incremental Effects of Justice Operationalizations on Procedural Fairness Perceptions Beyond Distributive Justice Effects Regression step Total R2 1. Distributive justice 2. Process control Leventhal criteria Interpersonal justice Informational justice .33* .57* .33* .24* .57* .03* .30* .26* .07* Note. N = 4,165 (based on the harmonic mean sample size of the Table 1 cells used in this regression). *p < .05. live justice than for the other three justice forms. This prediction was supported for two outcomes (outcome satisfac- tion and withdrawal) and was refuted for the remaining nine outcomes. Sweeney and McFarlin's (1993) two-factor model would predict higher unique effects of distributive justice for person-referenced outcomes and higher unique effects of procedural justice for system-referenced outcomes. This prediction was supported for five outcomes (outcome satisfaction, job satisfaction, organiza- tional commitment, system-referenced evaluation of authority, and performance) and was refuted for three outcomes (OCBOs, with- drawal, and negative reactions). The two-factor model was not relevant to the three agent-referenced outcomes (agent-referenced evaluation of authority, trust, and OCBIs). Bies and Moag's (1986) agent-system model would predict higher unique effects of interpersonal or informational justice for agent-referenced outcomes and higher unique effects of procedural justice for system-referenced outcomes. This prediction was sup- ported for five outcomes (job satisfaction, organizational commit- ment, agent-referenced evaluation of authority, OCBIs, and per- formance) and refuted for five outcomes (system-referenced evaluation of authority, trust, OCBOs, withdrawal, and negative reactions). The agent-system model was not relevant to person- referenced outcomes such as outcome satisfaction. Discussion This meta-analytic review, consisting of 120 separate meta- analyses of 183 empirical studies, explored three types of research questions to aid further theory development in the organizational justice literature. The first type of question was related to construct discrimination (i.e., how highly related are the various facets of organizational justice?). Process control and Leventhal criteria, the two original procedural justice Operationalizations, were highly correlated, although perhaps not as highly as one would think given that they are used interchangeably to express the same construct. Similarly, interpersonal and informational justice were highly correlated, but again not so highly that it seems prudent to lump them together under the "interactional justice" label. Indeed, their correlation was not significantly higher than the correlation between procedural justice and distributive justice, two constructs whose separation has become canon. Further analyses showed that the procedural justice-distributive justice relationship varies to some degree by how the researcher operationalizes the former. The relationship is strongest when an indirect combination measure is used and weaker when procedural fairness perceptions, Leventhal criteria, and especially process control are used. The second type of research question dealt with proactive re- search, which is concerned with creating procedural fairness per- ceptions by adhering to certain rules, such as providing process control, being consistent, treating people with sensitivity, or ex- plaining things adequately. Our results showed that the historical progression of proactive research on procedural justice has in fact contributed to our ability to promote procedural fairness percep- tions. The original conceptualization, Thibaut and Walker's (1975) process control, predicted procedural fairness perceptions, but Leventhal's (1980) criteria contributed significant incremental variance. Indeed, it is worth noting that the Leventhal criteria had a significantly stronger relationship to procedural fairness percep- tions than did process control. In fact, the Leventhal criteria are even more impressive when we consider that they predicted almost as much variance in procedural fairness perceptions as process control, even when entered in a later step in the regression analysis. The concepts of interpersonal and informational justice, drawn from the field's recent interest in interactional justice, show a more mixed pattern of results. Their correlations with procedural fair- ness perceptions were just as strong as the correlations for Lev- enthal criteria. However, although they explained significant in- cremental variance in fairness perceptions, their contribution was small in comparison with the contributions of the other justice facets. Thus, interpersonal and informational justice, when con- sidered alone, were powerful predictors of procedural fairness perceptions. When considered in conjunction with structural facets of procedural justice, their contribution was less important, partic- ularly in the case of informational justice. Perhaps this is not surprising considering that informational justice often provides the opportunity to judge structural qualities of procedural justice (Greenberg, 1993b). Because it is well known that the fairness of decision-making procedures is often judged according to the kinds of outcomes one receives (Lind & Tyler, 1988), it is also important to show that the various conceptualizations of procedural justice are important even after control for distributive justice. If this had not been the case, then the procedural justice literature would have contributed little over earlier work by Homans (1961), Adams (1965), Leventhal (1976), and Deutsch (1975). Our results showed that, when dis- tributive justice was controlled, only Leventhal criteria and inter- personal justice retained their explanatory power. Because process control added little, it is tempting to conclude that measuring it is unnecessary if distributive justice and Leventhal criteria are also being considered. Perhaps this is not surprising given Lind and Tyler's (1988) assertion that Leventhal's "representativeness" cri- terion includes the process control concept. Turning to our third type of research question, reactive research, we tested three separate reactive models: Leventhal's (1980) dis- tributive dominance model, Sweeney and McFarlin's (1993) two- factor model, and Bies and Moag's (1986) agent-system model. Support for these models can be evaluated by examining the relative effects of distributive, procedural, interpersonal, and in- formational justice on the basis of the size of their meta-analytic correlations, as well as their unique effects in the meta-analytic regressions. We find little support for the distributive dominance 436 COLQUITT, CONLON, WESSON, PORTER, AND NG Table 5 Relationships Between Organizational Justice Dimensions and Outcome Variables Dimension Broadly defined procedural justice Procedural fairness perceptions Process control Leventhal criteria Interpersonal justice Informational justice Indirect combination measure Distributive justice Broadly defined procedural justice Procedural fairness perceptions Process control Leventhal criteria Interpersonal justice Informational justice Indirect combination measure Distributive justice Broadly defined procedural justice Procedural fairness perceptions Process control Leventhal criteria Interpersonal justice Informational justice Indirect combination measure Distributive justice Broadly defined procedural justice Procedural fairness perceptions Process control Leventhal criteria Interpersonal justice Informational justice Indirect combination measure Distributive justice Broadly defined procedural justice Procedural fairness perceptions Process control Leventhal criteria Interpersonal justice Informational justice Indirect combination measure Distributive justice Broadly defined procedural justice Procedural fairness perceptions Process control Leventhal criteria Interpersonal justice Informational justice Indirect combination measure Distributive justice vart r (95% CI) rc (SDrJ k (N) (%) Outcome satisfaction .40 (.35, .46) .48 (.18) 30(8,073) 10.02 .45(36, .54) .53 (.17) 11(4,420) 6.59 .38 (.27, .48) .45 (.16) 8(1,774) 14.74 .25 (.13, .37) .32 (.17) 6(1,796) 13.03 .19 1 (301) .27 (.21, .33) .30 (.04) 4(1,404) 65.02 .47 (.39, .54) .54 (.15) 14(2,242) 18.87 .52 (.46, .59) .61 (.20) 28(9,321) 5.07 Organizational commitment .48 (.44, .52) .57 (.18) 53(33,455) 3.84 .32 (.25, .39) .37 (.16) 18(6,767) 9.58 .22 (.18, .27) .27 (.05) 7(2,898) 53.50 .26 (.22, .29) .30 (.00) 5(3,162) 100.00 .16 (.11,. 20) .19 (.00) 2(1,824) 100.00 .26 (.18, .34) .29 (.14) 10(3,968) 12.01 .55 (.51, .58) .65 (.10) 26(24,606) 6.10 .42 (.38, .47) .51 (.13) 24(27,805) 4.11 Evaluation of authority: Agent referenced .56 (.52, .59) .64 (.11) 33(20,034) 7.17 .53 (.46, .60) .60 (.13) 13(4,753) 8.76 .42(35, .50) .50 (.14) 10(3,436) 12.56 .53 (.41, .64) .63 (.17) 7(3,104) 4.86 .57 (.43, .71) .62 (.17) 5(2,534) 3.44 .58 (.46, .71) .65 (.21) 9(3,210) 3.21 .58 (.54, .62) .67 (.05) 9(13,850) 6.65 .53 (.46, .61) .59 (.15) 13(16,963) 1.96 OCBs: Individual referenced .19 (.16, .22) .22 (.00) 15(4,414) 100.00 .21 (.17, .25) .25 (.00) 2(1,872) 100.00 .16 (.12, .20) .21 (.00) 3(2,000) 100.00 .18 (.14, .23) .22 (.01) 3(2,108) 85.39 .23 (.18, .27) .29 (.00) 2(1,794) 100.00 .21 (.17, .26) .26 (.00) 2(1,883) 100.00 .19 (.14, .23) .22 (.02) 10(1,994) 90.18 .13 (.09, .17) .15 (.02) 6(2,633) 86.57 Withdrawal -.36 (-.42, -.31) -.46 (.20) 39(24,273) 4.12 -.27 (-.32, -.21) -.34 (.14) 21(7,344) 14.46 -.19 (-.27, -.10) -.24 (.14) 10(1,190) 39.94 -.23 (-30, -.16) -.29 (.07) 6(1,431) 50.87 -.02 (-.13, .09) -.02 (.00) 2(316) 100.00 -.21 (-34, -.07) -.24 (.21) 8(1,692) 11.42 -.44 (-.56, -.32) -.55 (.19) 6(14,392) 1.11 -.41 (-.46, -.37) -.50 (.12) 18(15,888) 7.45 Performance .30 (.21, .39) .36 (.29) 30(8,317) 4.83 .30 (.17, .43) .36(33) 18(6,925) 2.71 .14 (-.01, .29) .17 (.25) 8(1,002) 16.17 .08 (-.05, .21) .10 (.11) 3(501) 44.34 .03 (-.14, .20) .03 (.11) 2(389) 34.78 .11 (.00, .22) .13 (.11) 4(1,036) 29.79 .23 (.12, .35) .27 (.00) 7(1,084) 23.83 .13 (.03, .22) .15 (.18) 13(2,294) 18.43 varl r (95% CI) rc (S0rc) k (N) (%) Job satisfaction .51 (.46, .56) .62 (.18) 40(31,774) 2.88 .33 (.28, 38) .40 (.09) 11(4,958) 24.00 .30 (.25, 35) .37 (.05) 5(2,577) 50.39 36(33, .40) .42 (.00) 4(2,315) 100.00 31 (.26, 36) .35 (.02) 2(1,795) 65.96 38(34, .42) .43 (.00) 2(1,872) 100.00 .55 (.49, .61) .68 (.17) 22(25,221) 2.07 .46 (.42, .49) .56 (.09) 24(57,515) 8.31 Trust .52 (.44, .59) .61 (.20) 24 (4,522) 8.42 .56 (.49, .64) .62 (.08) 7(802) 39.78 .40(30, .50) .47 (.13) 7(1,031) 26.54 .58 (.09, .99) .65(38) 2(628) 1.23 .43(30, .57) .51 (.11) 3(487) 30.21 .55 (.45, .66) .64 (.18) 10(2,169) 8.02 .48 (.40, .57) .57 (.13) 8(1,735) 17.24 Evaluation of authority: System referenced 35 (31,. 40) .42 (.13) 25(9,708) 13.09 .45 (.42, .48) .51 (.12) 14(5,637) 11.63 .12 (.05, .20) .16 (.00) 3(663) 100.00 .19 (.02, .36) .22 (.15) 3(427) 29.27 .20 (.01, .38) .23 (.16) 3(469) 22.95 .42 (.29, .55) .47 (.15) 5(1,035) 14.94 .31 (.24, 38) .37 (.12) 11(3,790) 17.96 .30 (.24, 36) 37 (.12) 13(4,103) 20.64 OCBs: Organization referenced .23 (.19, .26) .27 (.04) 15(3,176) 78.62 .21 1 (140) .14 1 (206) .15 (.06, .24) .18 (.00) 2(431) 100.00 .18 1 (206) .25 (.20, .30) .30 (.06) 9(1,961) 63.06 .20 (.14, .26) .25 (.00) 5(903) 100.00 Negative reactions -.27 (-.33, -.21) -.31 (.18) 27(6,275) 1337 -33 (-.39, -.26) -.38 (.12) 13(3,563) 22.15 -.23 (-.27, -.19) -.30 (.00) 3(2,094) 100.00 -.28 (-.35, -.22) -.35 (.06) 5(2,308) 34.76 -30 (-.35, -.26) -.35 (.04) 7(2,707) 58.78 -.29 (-34, -.24) -.33 (.06) 8(2,731) 45.25 -.20 (-35, -.05) -.22 (.21) 7(1,807) 9.28 -.26 (-35, -.17) -30 (.17) 13(3,782) 12.27 Note, r = uncorrected population correlation; CI = confidence interval around uncorrected population correlation; rc = corrected population correlation; SOrc = standard deviation of corrected population correlation; k = number of studies; Vart = percentage of variance in rc explained by study artifacts; OCBs = organizational citizenship behaviors. META-ANALYTIC REVIEW OF ORGANIZATIONAL JUSTICE 437 Table 6 Unique Effects of Procedural, Interpersonal, Informational, and Distributive Justice on Outcome Variables Justice dimension Outcome variable Outcome satisfaction (N - 1,792) 0 Unique R2 Job satisfaction (N = 4,039) 0 Unique R2 Organizational commitment (N = 4,582) 0 Unique R2 Evaluation of authority: Agent-referenced (N = 4,517) 0 Unique R2 Evaluation of authority: System-referenced (N = 2,114) ft Unique R2 Trust^ = 1,711) 0 Unique R2 OCBs: Individual referenced (N = 3,192) ft Unique R2 OCBs: Organization referenced (N = 782) 0 Unique R2 Performance (N = 1,855) 0 Unique /f2 Withdrawal (AT = 1,919) 0 Unique ff2 Negative reactions (N = 4,039) 0 Unique R2 Procedural .17* .02* .48* .11* .42* .09* .01 .00 .30* .04* .31* .05* .06* .00* .12* .01* .56* .15* -.10* .01* -.06* .00* Interpersonal -.08* .00* -.09* .01* -.18* .02* .27* .04* -.19* .02* .19* .02* -.20* .02* .23* .02* -.18* .02* Informational .02 .00 .13* .01* .07* .00* .32* .05* .44* .10* .21* .03* .11* .01* .11* .01* .07* .00* -.21* .02* -.12* .01* Distributive .54* .18* .26* .04* .31* .06* .32* .06* .11* .01* .30* .05* -.01* .00 .12* .01* -.07 .00* -.51* .16* -.14* .01* Total R2 .39* .45* .35* .57* .31* .45* .09* .08* .19* .33* .16* Note. Sample sizes are based on the harmonic mean of the sample sizes for the correlations among the justice and outcome variables. The procedural justice variable includes process control, Leventhal criteria, and procedural fairness perceptions. OCBs = organizational citizenship behaviors. * p < .05. model, which predicts that distributive justice will have stronger effects than the other justice dimensions. This model was sup- ported for outcome satisfaction and withdrawal but not for any of the other nine outcomes. The two-factor model predicts that procedural justice will have stronger effects than distributive justice on system-referenced vari- ables but weaker effects than distributive justice on person- referenced variables. This model seemed to receive support only for person-referenced and system-referenced attitudes such as out- come satisfaction, job satisfaction, organizational commitment, and system-referenced evaluation of authority. The two-factor model's predictions were not supported for more behavioral vari- ables such as OCBs, withdrawal, and negative reactions. The only exception to this observation involved performance. Procedural justice was more capable of predicting performance than distrib- utive justice, which supports the two-factor model if performance is assumed to be a system-referenced outcome. The agent-system model predicts that interpersonal or informa- tional justice will have stronger effects than procedural justice on agent-referenced variables but weaker effects than procedural jus- tice on system-referenced variables. This model was supported for agent-referenced outcomes, including agent-referenced evaluation of authority and OCBIs, but not for trust, which was more related to procedural and distributive justice. The agent-system model was also supported for job satisfaction, organizational commit- ment, and performance. The model actually seems to underesti- mate the importance of interpersonal or informational justice for behavioral variables. Interpersonal or informational justice was a strong predictor of OCBOs, withdrawal, and negative reactions, which would not have been predicted on the basis of the agent- system model. Implications for the Organizational Justice Literature The conceptualization, measurement, and analysis of organiza- tional justice depend in large part on a given study's research question, as well as the sample or setting used to examine it. Nonetheless, the results of our review have some broad, general implications for the justice literature as a whole. Distinctiveness of justice dimensions. The construct discrimi- nation results suggest that procedural, interpersonal, and informa- tional justice are distinct constructs that can be empirically distin- 438 COLQUITT, CONLON, WESSON, PORTER, AND NG guished from one another. We would therefore call for a moratorium on indirect combination measures that combine the three justice dimensions into a single variable. Thirty-five of the studies included in our review used such measures (e.g., Brockner et al., 1995, 1997; Folger & Konovsky, 1989; Konovsky & Folger, 1991; Mansour-Cole & Scott, 1998; Skarlicki & Latham, 1997). Our review showed that procedural, interpersonal, and informa- tional justice have different correlates, and measuring the three separately allows for further differences among the dimensions to be examined. Measurement of justice dimensions. It is also critical that researchers devote more care and effort to the measurement of justice dimensions. Some of the articles we reviewed used mea- sures that assessed, among supervisors, granting subordinates voice, treating subordinates consistently, suppressing biases, being respectful, and providing explanations. Such measures were la- beled "interactional justice" (e.g., Moorman, 1991; Skarlicki & Latham, 1997), even though only the latter two are included in Bies and Moag's (1986) construct. Authors may have included such items on the basis of Folger and Bies's (1989) article on "managerial responsibilities" for procedural justice, which listed seven principles (process control, bias suppression, consistency, feedback, justification, truthfulness, and courtesy) managers should use to promote procedural justice. Not surprisingly, re- searchers using such measures have been forced to collapse the interactional justice measure with their procedural justice measure as a result of high intercorrelations (Mansour-Cole & Scott, 1998; Skarlicki & Latham, 1997). Thus, more attention should be paid to content validity, as in a recent study by Colquitt (2001), who developed scales for the justice dimensions based on the seminal works introducing them and validated the scales in two indepen- dent studies. Distinguishing justice content from justice source. Relatedly, future research should seek to separate the effects of justice con- tent from the effects of justice source. Procedurai justice can be a function of an organization, as when a formalized decision-making system provides process control or consistency as a result of the way in which it is structured (e.g., Adams-Roy & Barling, 1998; Ehlen, Magner, & Welker, 1999; Skarlicki et al., 1999). Procedural justice can also be a function of a decision-making agent, as when a manager takes steps to involve subordinates in decisions or treat subordinates consistently (e.g., Folger & Konovsky, 1989; Konovsky, Folger, & Cropanzano, 1987; Korsgaard, Schweiger, & Sapienza, 1995). Likewise, informational and interpersonal justice can be fostered through organizational policies and initiatives (e.g., Konovsky & Folger, 1991; Mansour-Cole & Scott, 1998; Tansky, 1993) or through the actions of a decision-making agent (e.g., Bies, Shapiro, & Cummings, 1988; Greenberg, 1994; Moorman, 1991). It is difficult to draw conclusions from studies comparing the effects of organization-originating procedural justice with agent-originating interpersonal or informational justice because source and content are confounded. Fortunately, recent research is beginning to examine this important issue by crossing justice source with justice content to assess their joint effects (Blader & Tyler, 2000; Byrne & Cropanzano, 2000; Masterson, Bartol, & Moye, 2000). Including multiple justice dimensions in single studies. Our results also clearly show that researchers can explain more out- come variance by including multiple justice dimensions within single studies, although there are some diminishing returns asso- ciated with this strategy. Our proactive research results showed that distributive justice, procedural justice (in terms of Leventhal criteria), interpersonal justice, and, to a lesser extent, informational justice each contribute uniquely to the creation of fairness percep- tions. Our reactive research results showed that procedural and distributive justice are sufficient to adequately predict several outcomes, and procedural and distributive justice were either the strongest or second strongest predictors of 15 outcomes. However, interpersonal and informational justice clearly contributed to the prediction of other outcomes. For example, one or both of these variables were strong independent predictors of behavioral out- comes such as OCBIs, OCBOs, withdrawal, and negative reac- tions. Informational justice was the strongest predictor of both agent-referenced and system-referenced evaluation of authority. These results suggest that researchers interested in most evaluation or behavioral outcomes should assess both structural and interac- tional facets of justice. Examining interactions among justice dimensions. In addition to explaining more outcome variance, including multiple dimen- sions will also allow for the testing of interaction effects. The interaction between procedural and distributive justice has been perhaps the most robust finding in the justice literature (Brockner & Wiesenfeld, 1996). Skarlicki and Folger (1997) further showed that procedural and interactional justice interact in predicting ORBs. These authors also found support for three-way interactions among procedural, interactional, and distributive justice. Such complex relationships do not map neatly onto reactive models such as the two-factor or agent-system model. However, the fact that moderators were present in almost all of the justice-outcome relationships suggests that more complex relationships may be the key to improving outcome prediction. Gaps in the existing literature. A final implication of our results resides in the gaps revealed by this review. A scan of Table 5 highlights areas where more research ought to be done. In terms of sheer number of studies, we note that procedural justice is much better represented in studies of satisfaction, commitment, evaluation of authorities, withdrawal, and negative reactions and relatively underrepresented in studies of performance, OCBs, and trust. We also note that interpersonal and informational justice have received less attention than distributive and procedural jus- tice, probably as a result of their more recent appearance in the justice literature. This is particularly evident for interpersonal justice, which has been assessed in 16 studies, as opposed to 31 studies for informational justice. As more researchers consider multiple justice dimensions in their work, these gaps should begin to be filled. Limitations This review has some limitations that should be noted. First, as in the primary studies on which our review is based, many of the variables were assessed with self-report measures. Thus, many of the relationships may be inflated because of same source bias. Second, any meta-analysis is subject to a variety of judgment calls META-ANALYTIC REVIEW OF ORGANIZATIONAL JUSTICE 439 (Wanous, Sullivan, & Malinak, 1989). Although we performed all coding in author dyads, it is possible that some of these judgment calls affected our results. Finally, the fact that meta-analysis re- quires the reporting of zero-order results meant that several im- portant justice articles could not be included in our review. In particular, many of Tyler's examinations of the relational model of justice had to be omitted (e.g., Tyler, 1989, 1994; Tyler et al., 1996). Conclusion In a review of the organizational justice literature, Greenberg (1993a) suggested that the field was in a state of "intellectual adolescence." This adolescence, though marked by many advance- ments, is also characterized by "stumbling awkwardness" due to underdeveloped research agendas and the absence of underlying theory (Greenberg, 1993a, p. 139). In an earlier review, Greenberg (1990b) echoed these sentiments, noting that the field was years away from the final stage of Reichers and Schneider's (1990) construct life cycle. That final stage, termed "consolidation and accommodation," is characterized by a reduction in controversies and an increase in agreement about definitions, antecedents, and consequences. Meta-analytic reviews, according to Greenberg (1990b), can help create such consolidation. Thus, we hope that the review presented in this article can help the field enter a more mature stage, as research on justice enters the new millennium. References References marked with an asterisk indicate studies included in the meta-analysis. Adams, J. S. (1965). Inequity in social exchange. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 2, pp. 267-299). New York: Academic Press. *Adams-Roy, J., & Barling, J. (1998). Predicting the decision to confront or report sexual harassment. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 19, 329-336. Alexander, S., & Ruderman, M. (1987). The role of procedural and distributive justice in organizational behavior. Social Justice Re- search, 1, 177-198. Allen, N. J., & Meyer, J. P. (1990). The measurement and antecedents of affective, continuance, and normative commitment to the organization. Journal of Occupational Psychology, 63, 1-18. *Ambrose, M. L., & Kulik, C. T. (1989). The influence of social compar- isons on perceptions of procedural fairness. Journal of Business and Psychology, 4, 129-138. *Aquino, K. (1995). Relationships among pay inequity, perceptions of procedural justice, and organizational citizenship. Employee Responsi- bilities and Rights Journal, 8, 21-33. *Aquino, K., Griffeth, R. W., Allen, D. G., & Horn, P. W. (1997). Integrating justice constructs into the turnover process: A test of a referent cognitions model. Academy of Management Journal, 40, 1208- 1227. *Armstrong-Stassen, M. (1998). The effect of gender and organizational level on how survivors appraise and cope with organizational downsiz- ing. Journal of Applied Behavioral Science, 34, 125-142. *Austin, W., McGinn, N. C., & Susmilch, C. (1980). Internal standards revisited: Effects of social comparisons and expectancies on judgments of fairness and satisfaction. Journal of Experimental Social Psychol- ogy, 16, 426-441. *Ball, G. A., Trevino, L. K. & Sims, H. P., Jr. (1993). Justice and organizational punishment: Attitudinal outcomes of disciplinary events. Social Justice Research, 6, 39-67. *Ball, G. A., Trevino, L. K., & Sims, H. P., Jr. (1994). Just and unjust punishment: Influences on subordinate performance and citizenship. Academy of Management Journal, 37, 299-322. *Barclay, J. H., & Harland, L. K. (1995). Peer performance appraisals: The impact of rater competence, rater location, and rating correctability on fairness perceptions. Group and Organization Management, 20, 39-60. *Barling, J., & Phillips, M. (1993). Interactional, formal and distributive justice in the workplace: An exploratory study. Journal of Psychology, 127, 649-656. Bazerman, M. H., Schroth, H., Shah, P., Diekmann, K., & Tenbrunsel, A. (1994). The inconsistent role of comparison others and procedural jus- tice in reactions to hypothetical job descriptions; Implications for job acceptance decisions. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 60, 326-352. *Bennett, N., Martin, C. L., Bies, R. J., & Brockner, J. (1995). Coping with a layoff: A longitudinal study of victims. Journal of Management, 21, 1025-1040. *Bennett, R. J. (1998). Taking the sting out of the whip: Reactions to consistent punishment for unethical behavior. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Applied, 4, 248-262. *Bies, R. J. (1987). Beyond "voice": The influence of decision-maker justification and sincerity on procedural fairness judgments. Represen- tative Research in Social Psychology, 17, 3-14. *Bies, R. J., Martin, C. L., & Brockner, J. (1993). Just laid off, but still a "good citizen?" Only if the process is fair. Employee Responsibilities and Rights Journal, 6, 227-238. Bies, R. J., & Moag, J. F. (1986). Interactional justice: Communication criteria of fairness. In R. J. Lewicki, B. H. Sheppard, & M. H. Bazerman (Eds.), Research on negotiations in organizations (Vol. 1, pp. 43-55). Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. *Bies, R. J., & Shapiro, D. L. (1987). Interactional fairness judgments: The influence of causal accounts. Social Justice Research, I, 199-218. *Bies, R. J., & Shapiro, D. L. (1988). Voice and justification: Their influence on procedural fairness judgments. Academy of Management Journal, 31, 676-685. *Bies, R. J., Shapiro, D. L., & Cummings, L. L. (1988). Causal accounts and managing organizational conflict: Is it enough to say it's not my fault? Communication Research, 15, 381-399. Blader, S. L., & Tyler, T. R. (2000, August). A four-component model of procedural justice: What makes a process fair in work settings? Paper presented at the 59th Annual Meeting of the National Academy of Management, Toronto, Ontario, Canada. Blau, P. M. (1964). Exchange and power in social life. New York: Wiley. *Bobocel, D. R., Agar, S. E., Meyer, J. P., & Irving, P. G. (1998). Managerial accounts and fairness perceptions in conflict resolution: Differentiating the effects of minimizing responsibility and providing justification. Basic and Applied Social Psychology, 20, 133-143. *Bobocel, D. R., & Farrell, A. C. (1996). Sex-based promotion decisions and interactional fairness: Investigating the influence of managerial accounts. Journal of Applied Psychology, 81, 22-35. Borman, W. C. (1991). Job behavior, performance, and effectiveness. In M. D. Dunnette & L. M. Hough (Eds.), Handbook of industrial and organizational psychology (2nd ed., Vol. 2, pp. 271-326). Palo Alto, CA: Consulting Psychologists Press. *Brockner, J., DeWitt, R. L., Grover, S., & Reed, T. (1990). When it is especially important to explain why: Factors affecting the relationship between managers' explanations of a layoff and survivors' reactions to the layoff. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 26, 389-407. *Brockner, J., Konovsky, M., Cooper-Schneider, R., Folger, R., Martin, C., & Bies, R. J. (1994). Interactive effects of procedural justice and 440 COLQUITT, CONLON, WESSON, PORTER, AND NO outcome negativity on victims and survivors of job loss. Academy of Management Journal, 37, 397-409. *Brockner, J., Siegel, P. A., Daly, J. P., & Martin, C. (1997). When trust matters: The moderating effect of outcome favorability. Administrative Science Quarterly, 42, 558-583. *Brockner, J., Tyler, T. M, & Cooper-Schneider, R. (1992). The influence of prior commitment to an institution on reactions to perceived unfair- ness: The higher they are, the harder they fall. Administrative Science Quarterly, 37, 241-261. Brockner, J., & Wiesenfeld, B. M. (1996). An integrative framework for explaining reactions to decisions: Interactive effects of outcomes and procedures. Psychological Bulletin, 120, 189-208. *Brockner, J., Wiesenfeld, B. M., & Martin, C. L. (1995). Decision frame, procedural justice, and survivors' reactions to job layoffs. Organiza- tional Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 63, 59-68. *Brockner, J., Wiesenfeld, B. M., Reed, T., Grover, S., & Martin, C. (1993). Interactive effect of job content and context on the reactions of layoff survivors. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 64, 187-197. Byrne, Z. S., & Cropanzano, R. S. (2000, April). To which do I attribute this fairness? Differential effects of multi-foci justice on organizational work behaviors. Paper presented at the 15th Annual Conference of the Society for Industrial and Organizational Psychology, New Orleans, LA. *Cobb, A. T., & Frey, F. M. (1996). The effects of leader fairness and pay outcomes on superior/subordinate relations. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 26, 1401-1426. *Cobb, A. T., Vest. M., & Hills, F. (1997). Who delivers justice? Source perceptions of procedural fairness. Journal of Applied Social Psychol- ogy, 27, 1021-1040. Cohen, J.. & Cohen, P. (1983). Applied multiple regression/correlation analysis for the behavioral sciences. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. *Colquitt, J. A. (1999). The impact of procedural justice in teams: An analysis of task, team, and member moderators. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Michigan State University, East Lansing. *Colquitt, J. A. (2000). Justice in teams: An analysis of antecedents and consequences. Unpublished manuscript. *Colquitt, J. A. (2001). On the dimensionality of organizational justice: A construct validation of a measure. Journal of Applied Psychology, 86, 386-400. *Colquitt, J. A., & Chertkoff, J. M. (1996, April). Explaining injustice: The interactive effect of explanation and outcome on fairness perceptions and task motivation. Paper presented at the 11th Annual Conference of the Society for Industrial and Organizational Psychology, San Diego, CA. Colquitt, J. A., LePine, J. A., & Noe, R. A. (2000). Toward an integrative theory of training motivation: A meta-analytic path analysis of 20 years of research. Journal of Applied Psychology, 85, 678-707. *Conlon, D. E. (1993). Some tests of the self-interest and group value models of procedural justice: Evidence from an organizational appeal procedure. Academy of Management Journal, 36, 1109-1124. *Conlon, D. E., & Fasolo, P. M. (1990). Influence of speed of third-party intervention and outcome on negotiator and constituent fairness judg- ments. Academy of Management Journal, 33, 833-846. *Conlon, D. E., & Lynch, P. D. (1997, June). The role of contracts and explanations on justice judgments and agent compensation. Paper pre- sented at the I0th Annual Conference of the International Association for Conflict Management, Bonn, Germany. *Conlon, D. E., & Murray, N. M. (1996). Customer perceptions of corpo- rate responses to product complaints: The role of explanations. Academy of Management Journal, 39, 1040-1056. *Conlon, D. E., & Parks, J. M. (1999). Effects of resources and reward allocation rules on justice judgments. Unpublished manuscript. *Conlon, D. E., & Ross, W. H. (1993). The effects of partisan third parties on negotiator behavior and outcome perceptions. Journal of Applied Psychology, 78, 280-290. *Conlon, D. E., & Ross, W. H. (1997). Appearances do count: The effects of outcomes and explanations on disputant fairness judgments and supervisory evaluations. International Journal of Conflict Manage- ment, 8, 5-31. Cropanzano, R., & Ambrose, M. L. (2001). Procedural and distributive justice are more similar than you think: A monistic perspective and a research agenda. In J. Greenberg & R. Cropanzano (Eds.), Advances in organizational justice (pp. 119-151). Lexington, MA: New Lexington Press. Cropanzano, R., & Greenberg, J. (1997). Progress in organizational justice: Tunneling through the maze. In C. Cooper & I. Robertson (Eds.), International review of industrial and organizational psychology (pp. 317-372). New York: Wiley. *Cropanzano, R., & Konovsky, M. A. (1996). Resolving the justice di- lemma by improving the outcomes: The case of employee drug screen- ing. Journal of Business and Psychology, 11, 239-263. *Cropanzano, R., & Prehar, C. A. (1999, April). Using social exchange theory to distinguish procedural from interactional justice. Paper pre- sented at the 14th Annual Conference of the Society for Industrial and Organizational Psychology, Atlanta, GA. Cudeck, R. (1989). Analysis of correlation matrices using covariance structure models. Psychological Bulletin, 105, 317-327. *Dailey, R. C., & Kirk, D. J. (1992). Distributive and procedural justice as antecedents of job dissatisfaction and intent to turnover. Human Rela- tions, 45, 305-317. *Daly, J. P. (1995). Explaining changes to employees: The influence of justifications and change outcomes on employees' fairness judgments. Journal of Applied Behavioral Science, 31, 415-428. *Daly, J. P., & Geyer, P. D. (1994). The role of fairness in implementing large-scale change: Employee evaluations of process and outcome in seven facility relocations. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 15, 623- 638. *Davy, J. A., Kinicki, A. J., & Scheck, C. L. (1991). Developing and testing a model of survivor responses to layoffs. Journal of Vocational Behavior, 38, 302-317. Deutsch, M. (1975). Equity, equality, and need: What determines which value will be used as the basis of distributive justice? Journal of Social Issues, 31, 137-150. *DeWitt, R. L., Trevino, L. K., & Mollica, K. A. (1998). The influence of eligibility on employees' reactions to voluntary workforce reductions. Journal of Management, 24, 593-613. *Dittrich, J. E., & Carrell, M. R. (1979). Organizational equity perceptions, employee job satisfaction, and department absence and turnover rates. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 24, 29-40. *Donovan, M. A., Drasgow, F., & Munson, L. J. (1998). The Perceptions of Fair Interpersonal Treatment Scale: Development and validation of a measure of interpersonal treatment in the workplace. Journal of Applied Psychology, 83, 683-692. *Dulebotm, J. H., & Ferris, G. R. (1999). The role of influence tactics in perceptions of performance evaluations' fairness. Academy of Manage- ment Journal, 42, 288-303. *Dulebohn, J. H., & Martocchio, J. J. (1998). Employee perceptions of the fairness of work group incentive pay plans. Journal of Management, 24, 469-488. *Earley, P. C., & Lind, E. A. (1987). Procedural justice and participation in task selection: The role of control in mediating justice judgments. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 52, 1148-1160. *Ehlen, C. R., Magner, N. R., & Welker, R. B. (1999). Testing for interactive effects of outcome favourability and procedural fairness on members' reactions towards a voluntary professional organization. Jour- nal of Occupational and Organizational Psychology, 72, 147-161. META-ANALYTIC REVIEW OF ORGANIZATIONAL JUSTICE 441 *Farh, J., Earley, P. C., & Lin, S. (1997). Impetus for action: A cultural analysis of justice and organizational citizenship behavior in Chinese society. Administrative Science Quarterly, 42, 421-444. Folger, R. (1977). Distributive and procedural justice: Combined impact of "voice" and improvement on experienced inequity Journal of Person- ality and Social Psychology, 35, 108-119. Folger, R. (1987). Distributive and procedural justice in the workplace. Social Justice Research, 1, 143-159. Folger, R., & Bies, R. J. (1989). Managerial responsibilities and procedural justice. Employee Responsibilities and Rights Journal, 2, 79-89. Folger, R., & Cropanzano, R. (1998). Organizational justice and human resource management. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. *FoIger, R., & Konovsky, M. A. (1989). Effects of procedural and distrib- utive justice on reactions to pay raise decisions. Academy of Manage- ment Journal, 32, 115-130. *Folger, R., & Martin, C. (1986). Relative deprivation and referent cog- nitions: Distributive and procedural justice effects. Journal of Experi- mental Social Psychology, 22, 531-546. *Folger, R., Rosenfield, D., Grove, J., & Corkran, L. (1979). Effects of "voice" and peer opinions and responses to inequity. Journal of Person- ality and Social Psychology, 37, 2253-2261. *Folger, R., Rosenfield, D., Hays, R., & Grove, R. (1978). Justice vs. justification effects on productivity: Reconciling equity and dissonance findings. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 22, 465-473. *Folger, R., & Skarlicki, D. P. (1998). When tough times make tough bosses: Managerial distancing as a function of layoff blame. Academy of Management Journal, 41, 79-87. *Frost, S. E. (Ed.). (1972). Masterworks of philosophy (Vol. 1, pp. 135- 140). Boston: McGraw-Hill. *Fryxell, G. E., & Gordon, M. E. (1989). Workplace justice and job satisfaction as predictors of satisfaction with union and management. Academy of Management Journal, 32, 851-866. *Gellatly, I. R. (1995). Individual and group determinants of employee absenteeism: Test of a causal model. Journal of Organizational Behav- ior, 16, 469-485. *George, J. M. (1991). State or trait: Effects of positive mood on prosocial behaviors at work. Journal of Applied Psychology, 76, 299-307. *Giacobbe-Miller, J. (1995). A test of the group values and control models of procedural justice from the competing perspectives of labor and management. Personnel Psychology, 48, 115-142. *Giles, W. F., Findley, H. M., & Field, H. S. (1997). Procedural fairness in performance appraisal: Beyond the review session. Journal of Business and Psychology, 11, 493-506. *Gilliland, S. W. (1994). Effects of procedural and distributive justice on reactions to a selection system. Journal of Applied Psychology, 79, 691-701. *Gilliland, S. W., & Beckstein, B. A. (1996). Procedural and distributive justice in the editorial review process. Personnel Psychology, 49, 669- 691. *Gilliland, S. W., Benson, L., & Schepers, D. H. (1998). A rejection threshold in justice evaluations: Effects on judgment and decision- making. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 76, 113-131. *Gordon, M. E., & Bowlby, R. L. (1988). Propositions about grievance settlements: Finally, consultation with grievants. Personnel Psychol- ogy, 41, 107-123. *Gordon, M. E., & Fryxell, G. E. (1989). Voluntariness of association as a moderator of the importance of procedural and distributive justice. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 19, 993-1009. Graen, G. B., & Scandura, T. (1987). Toward a psychology of dyadic organizing. In L. L. Cummings & B. M. Staw (Eds.), Research in organizational behavior (Vol. 9, pp. 175-208). Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. *Greenberg, J. (1987a). Reactions to procedural injustice in payment distributions: Do the means justify the ends? Journal of Applied Psy- chology, 72, 55-61. Greenberg, J. (1987b). A taxonomy of organizational justice theories. Academy of Management Review, 12, 9-22. Greenberg, J. (1990a). Employee theft as a reaction to underpayment inequity: The hidden cost of pay cuts. Journal of Applied Psychol- ogy, 75, 561-568. Greenberg, J. (1990b). Organizational justice: Yesterday, today, and to- morrow. Journal of Management, 16, 399-432. Greenberg, J. (1993a). The intellectual adolescence of organizational jus- tice: You've come a long way, maybe. Social Justice Research, 6, 135-148. Greenberg, J. (1993b). The social side of fairness: Interpersonal and informational classes of organizational justice. In R. Cropanzano (Ed.), Justice in the workplace: Approaching fairness in human resource management (pp. 79-103). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. *Greenberg, J. (1993c). Stealing in the name of justice: Informational and interpersonal moderators of theft reactions to underpayment inequity. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 54, 81-103. *Greenberg, J. (1994). Using socially fair treatment to promote acceptance of a work site smoking ban. Journal of Applied Psychology, 79, 288- 297. *Grienberger, I. V., Rutte, C. G., & Van Knippenberg, A. F. M. (1997). Influence of social comparisons of outcomes and procedures on fairness judgments. Journal of Applied Psychology, 82, 913-919. *Griffeth, R. W., Vecchio, R. P., & Logan, J. W. (1989). Equity theory and interpersonal attraction. Journal of Applied Psychology, 74, 394-401. *Hagedoorn, M., Buunk, B. P., & Van de Vliert, E. (1998). Opening the black box between justice and reactions to unfavorable outcomes in the workplace. Social Justice Research, 11, 41-57. *Hammer, T. H., Landau, J. C., & Stern, R. N. (1981). Absenteeism when workers have a voice: The case of employee ownership. Journal of Applied Psychology, 66, 561-573. *Harrison, D. A., McLaughlin, M. E., & Coalter, T. M. (1996). Context, cognition, and common method variance: Psychometric and verbal pro- tocol evidence. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Pro- cesses, 68, 246-261. Horn, P. W., Caranikas-Walker, F., Prussia, G. E., & Griffeth, R. W. (1992). A meta-analytical structural equations analysis of a model of employee turnover. Journal of Applied Psychology, 77, 890-909. *Hom, P. W., Griffeth, R. W., & Sellaro, C. L. (1984). The validity of Mobley's (1977) model of employee turnover. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 34, 141-174. Homans, G. (1961). Social behaviour: Its elementary forms. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Hunter, J. E., & Schmidt, F. L. (1990). Methods ofmeta-analysis. Newbury Park, CA: Sage. *Jones, F. F., Scarpello, V., & Bergmann, T. (1999). Pay procedures: What makes them fair? Journal of Occupational and Organizational Psychol- ogy, 72, 129-145. *Joy, V. L., & Witt, L. A. (1992). Delay of gratification as a moderator of the procedural justice-distributive justice relationship. Group and Orga- nization Management, 17, 297-308. *Kanfer, R., Sawyer, J. E., Earley, P. C., & Lind, E. A. (1987). Fairness and participation in evaluation procedures: Effects on task attitudes and performance. Social Justice Research, I, 235-249. *Karambayya, R., & Brett, J. M. (1989). Managers handling disputes: Third-party roles and perceptions of fairness. Academy of Management Journal, 32, 687-704. 442 COLQUITT, CONLON, WESSON, PORTER, AND NO *KelIer, T., & Dansereau, F. (1995). Leadership and empowerment: A social exchange perspective. Human Relations, 48, 127-146. *Kidwell, R. E., & Bennett, N. (1994). Employee reactions to electronic control systems: The role of procedural fairness. Group and Organiza- tion Management, 19, 203-218. *Kim, W. C., & Mauborgne, R. A. (1993). Procedural justice, attitudes, and subsidiary top management compliance with multinationals' corpo- rate strategic decisions. Academy of Management Journal, 36, 502-526. *Kim, W. C., & Mauborgne, R. A. (1996). Procedural justice and manag- ers' in-role and extra-role behavior: The case of the multinational. Management Science, 42, 499-515. *King, W. C., Jr., Miles, E. W., & Day, D. D. (1993). A test and refinement of the equity sensitivity construct. Journal of Organizational Behav- ior, 14, 301-317. *Konovsky, M. A., & Cropanzano, R. (1991). Perceived fairness of em- ployee drug testing as a predictor of employee attitudes and job perfor- mance. Journal of Applied Psychology, 76, 698-707. *Konovsky, M. A., & Folger, R. (1991). The effects of procedures, social accounts, and benefits level on victims' layoff reactions. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 21, 630-650. *Konovsky, M. A., Folger, R., & Cropanzano, R. (1987). Relative effects of procedural and distributive justice on employee attitudes. Represen- tative Research in Social Psychology, 17, 15-24. *Konovsky, M. A., & Pugh, S. D. (1994). Citizenship behavior and social exchange. Academy of Management Journal, 37, 656-669. *Korsgaard, M. A., & Roberson, L. (1995). Procedural justice in perfor- mance evaluation: The role of instrumental and non-instrumental voice in performance appraisal discussions. Journal of Management, 21, 657- 669. *Korsgaard, M. A., Roberson, L., & Rymph, R. D. (1998). What motivates fairness? The role of subordinate assertive behavior on managers' inter- actional fairness. Journal of Applied Psychology, 83, 731-744. *Korsgaard, M. A., Schweiger, D. M., & Sapienza, H. J. (1995). Building commitment, attachment, and trust in strategic decision-making teams: The role of procedural justice. Academy of Management Journal, 38, 60-84. *Latack, J. C., Josephs, S. L., Roach, B. L., & Levine, M. D. (1987). Carpenter apprentices: Comparison of career transitions for men and women. Journal of Applied Psychology, 72, 393-400. *LaTour, S. (1978). Determinants of participant and observer satisfaction with adversary and inquisitorial modes of adjudication. Journal of Per- sonality and Social Psychology, 12, 1531—1545. *Lawson, M. B., & Angle, H. L. (1998). Upon reflection: Commitment, satisfaction, and regret after a corporate relocation. Group and Organi- zation Management, 23, 289-317. *Lee, C., & Farh, J. L. (1999). The effects of gender in organizational justice perception. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 20, 133-143. *Leung, K., & Li, W. (1990). Psychological mechanisms of process- control effects. Journal of Applied Psychology, 75, 613-620. *Leventhal, G. S. (1976). The distribution of rewards and resources in groups and organizations. In L. Berkowitz & W. Walster (Eds.), Ad- vances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 9, pp. 91-131). New York: Academic Press. Leventhal, G. S. (1980). What should be done with equity theory? New approaches to the study of fairness in social relationships. In K. Gergen, M. Greenberg, & R. Willis (Eds.), Social exchange: Advances in theory and research (pp. 27-55). New York: Plenum. Leventhal, G. S., Karuza, J., & Fry, W. R. (1980). Beyond fairness: A theory of allocation preferences. In G. Mikula (Ed.), Justice and social interaction (pp. 167-218). New York: Springer-Verlag. *Levy, P. E., & Williams, J. R. (1998). The role of perceived system knowledge in predicting appraisal reactions, job satisfaction, and orga- nizational commitment. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 19, 53-65. *Lind, E. A., Kulik, C. T., Ambrose, M. A., & de Vera Park, M. V. (1993). Individual and corporate dispute resolution: Using procedural fairness as a decision heuristic. Administrative Science Quarterly, 38, 224—251. *Lind, E. A., Lissak, R. L, & Conlon, D. F. (1983). Decision control and process control effects on procedural fairness judgments. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 13, 338-350. Lind, E. A., & Tyler, T. R. (1988). The social psychology of procedural justice. New York: Plenum. *Lind, E. A., Tyler, T. R., & Huo, Y. J. (1997). Procedural context and culture: Variation in the antecedents of procedural justice judgments. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 73, 767-780. *Lowe, R. H., & Vodanovich, S. J. (1995). A field study of distributive and procedural justice as predictors of satisfaction and organizational com- mitment. Journal of Business and Psychology, W, 99-114. *Macan, T. H., Avedon, M. J., Paese, M., & Smith, D. B. (1994). The effects of applicants' reactions to cognitive ability tests and an assess- ment center. Personnel Psychology, 47, 715-738. *Magner, N. R., Rahman, M., & Welker, R. B. (1996). The interactive effect of outcome favorability and procedural justice in work resource allocation on work performance. Journal of Applied Social Psychol- ogy, 26, 825-842. *Mansour-Cole, D. M., & Scott, S. G. (1998). Hearing it through the grapevine: The influence of source, leader-relations, and legitimacy on survivors' fairness perceptions. Personnel Psychology, 51, 25-54. *Mark, M. M. (1985). Expectations, procedural justice, and alternative reactions to being deprived of a desired outcome. Journal of Experi- mental Social Psychology, 21, 114—137. *Martin, C. L., & Bennett, N. (1996). The role of justice judgments in explaining the relationship between job satisfaction and organizational commitment. Group and Organization Management, 21, 84-104. *Martin, C. L., Parsons, C. K., & Bennett, N. (1995). The influence of employee involvement program membership during downsizing: Atti- tudes toward the employer and the union. Journal of Management, 21, 879-890. *Martin, J. E., & Peterson, M. M. (1987). Two-tier wage structures: Implications for equity theory. Academy of Management Journal, 30, 297-315. *Martocchia, J. J., & Judge, T. A. (1995). When we don't see eye to eye: Discrepancies between supervisors and subordinates in absence disci- plinary procedures. Journal of Management, 21, 251-278. Masterson, S. S., Bartol, K. M., & Moye, N. (2000, April). Interactional and procedural justice: Type versus source of fairness. Paper presented at the 15th Annual Conference of the Society for Industrial and Orga- nizational Psychology, New Orleans, LA. *Masterson, S. S., Lewis, K., Goldman, B. M., & Taylor, M. S. (2000). Integrating justice and social exchange: The differing effects of fair procedures and treatment on work relationships. Academy of Manage- ment Journal, 43, 738-748. Mathieu, J. E., & Zajac, D. M. (1990). A review and meta-analysis of the antecedents, correlates, and consequences of organizational commit- ment. Psychological Bulletin, 108, 172-195. *McFarIin, D. B., & Sweeney, P. D. (1992). Distributive and procedural justice as predictors of satisfaction with personal and organizational outcomes. Academy of Management Journal, 35, 626—637. *McFarlin, D. B., & Sweeney, P. D. (1996). Does having a say matter only if you get your way? Instrumental and value-expressive effects of employee voice. Basic and Applied Social Psychology, 18, 289-303. *Miles, J. A., & Klein, H. J. (1998). The fairness of assigning group members to tasks. Group and Organization Management, 23, 71-96. *Miller, M. L. (1989). Process and decision control in the work place: Separate effects, independence from distributive justice, and tests of explanatory mechanisms. Basic and Applied Social Psychology, 10, 337-354. META-ANALYTIC REVIEW OF ORGANIZATIONAL JUSTICE 443 *Moorman, R. H. (1991). Relationship between organizational justice and organizational citizenship behaviors: Do fairness perceptions influence employee citizenship? Journal of Applied Psychology, 76, 845-855. *Moorman, R. H., & Blakely, G. L. (1995). Individualism-collectivism as an individual difference predictor of organizational citizenship behavior. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 16, 127-142. *Moorman, R. H., Blakely, G. L., & Niehoff, B. P. (1998). Does perceived organizational support mediate the relationship between procedural jus- tice and organizational citizenship behavior? Academy of Management Journal, 41, 351-357. *Moorman, R. H., Niehoff, B. P., & Organ, D. W. (1993). Treating employees fairly and organizational citizenship behavior: Sorting the effects of job satisfaction, organizational commitment, and procedural justice. Employee Responsibilities and Rights Journal, 6, 209-225. *Mossholder, K. W., Bennett, N., Kemery, E. R., & Wesolowski, M. A. (1998). Relationships between bases of power and work reactions: The mediational role of procedural justice. Journal of Management, 24, 533-552. *Mossholder, K. W., Bennett, N., & Martin, C. L. (1998). A multilevel analysis of procedural justice context. Journal of Organizational Behav- ior, 19, 131-141. *Moye, N. A., Masterson, S. S., & Bartol, K. M. (1997, August). Differ- entiating antecedents and consequences of procedural and interactional justice: Empirical evidence in support of separate constructs. Paper presented at the 56th Annual Meeting of the National Academy of Management, Boston, MA. *Newman, K. L. (1993). Procedural justice and ethical decision making. Social Justice Research, 6, 113-134. *Niehoff, B. P., & Moorman, R. H. (1993). Justice as a mediator of the relationship between methods of monitoring and organizational citizen- ship behavior. Academy of Management Journal, 36, 527-556. *Ogilvie. J. R. (1986). The role of human resource management practices in predicting organizational commitment. Group and Organization Stud- ies, 11. 335-359. *Olson-Buchanan, J. B. (1996). Voicing discontent: What happens to the grievance filer after the grievance? Journal of Applied Psychology, 81, 52-63. Organ, D. W. (1990). The motivational basis of organizational citizenship behavior. In L. L. Cummings & B. M. Staw (Eds.), Research in orga- nizational behavior (Vol. 12, pp. 43-72). Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. *Parker, C. P., Baltes, B. B., & Christiansen, N. D. (1997). Support for affirmative action, justice perceptions, and work attitudes: A study of gender and racial-ethnic group differences. Journal of Applied Psychol- ogy, 82. 376-389. Pillutla, M., & Murnighan, J. K. (1999). On fairness and justice in bargaining and in allocation decisions and procedures. Unpublished manuscript. *Ployhart, R. E., & Ryan, A. M. (1997). Toward an explanation of applicant reactions: An examination of organizational justice and attri- bution frameworks. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Pro- cesses, 72, 308-335. *Ployhart, R. E., & Ryan, A. M. (1998). Applicants' reactions to the fairness of selection procedures: The effects of positive rule violations and time of measurement. Journal of Applied Psychology, 83, 3-16. *Ployhart, R. E., Ryan, A. M., & Bennett, M. (1999). Explanations for selection decisions: Applicants' reactions to informational and sensitiv- ity features of explanations. Journal of Applied Psychology, 84, 87-106. Podsakoff, P. M., MacKenzie, S. B., & Bommer, W. H. (1996). Meta- analysis of the relationships between Kerr and Jermier's substitutes for leadership and employee job attitudes, role perceptions, and perfor- mance. Journal of Applied Psychology, 81, 380-399. *Pond, S. B., Ill, Nacoste, R. W., Mohr, M. F., & Rodriguez, C. M. (1997). The measurement of organizational citizenship behavior: Are we assum- ing too much? Journal of Applied Psychology, 27, 1527-1554. *Porter, C. O. L. H., Conlon, D. E., & Barber, A. E. (1999, August). Effects of justice in salary negotiations on recruitment outcomes: A laboratory experiment. Paper presented at the 58th Annual Meeting of the Academy of Management, Chicago, IL. *Rasinski, D. A. (1990). Contextualizing procedural fairness: Factors mediating the effect of process control on leadership evaluation in organizations. Basic and Applied Social Psychology, 11, 459-477. Reichers, A. E., & Schneider, B. (1990). Climate and culture: Life cycles of constructs. In B. Schneider (Ed.), Organizational climate and culture (pp. 5-39). San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. *Richard, O. C., & Kirby, S. L. (1998). Women recruits' perceptions of workforce diversity program selection decisions: A procedural justice examination. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 28, 183-188. Ryan, A. (1993). Justice. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. *Sapienza, H. J., & Korsgaard, M. A. (1996). Procedural justice in entrepreneur-investor relations. Academy of Management Journal, 39, 544-574. *Scandura, T. A. (1997). Mentoring and organizational justice: An empir- ical investigation. Journal of Vocational Behavior, 51, 58-69. *Scarpello, V., & Jones, F. F. (1996). Why justice matters in compensation decision making. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 17, 285-299. *Schappe, S. P. (1998). The influence of job satisfaction, organizational commitment, and fairness perceptions on organizational citizenship be- havior. Journal of Psychology, 132, 277-290. *Schaubroeck, J., May, D. R., & Brown, F. W. (1994). Procedural justice explanations and employee reactions to economic hardship: A field experiment. Journal of Applied Psychology, 79, 455-460. *Scher, S. J. (1997). Measuring the consequences of injustice. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 23, 482-497. *Schmidt, F. L., Hunter, J. E., & Outerbridge, A. N. (1986). Impact of job experience and ability on job knowledge, work sample performance, and supervisory ratings of job performance. Journal of Applied Psychol- ogy, 71, 432-439. *Schminke, M., Ambrose, M. L., & Noel, T. W. (1997). The effect of ethical frameworks on perceptions of organizational justice. Academy of Management Journal, 40, 1190-1207. *Schmitt, M. (1996). Individual differences in sensitivity to befallen in- justice (SBI). Personality and Individual Differences, 21, 3-20. *Shapiro, D. L. (1991). The effects of explanations on negative reactions to deceit. Administrative Science Quarterly, 36, 614-630. *Shapiro, D. L., & Brett, J. M. (1993). Comparing three processes under- lying judgments of procedural justice: A field study of mediation and arbitration. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 6, 1167- 1177. *Shapiro, D. L., Buttner, E. H., & Barry, B. (1994). Explanations: What factors enhance their perceived adequacy? Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 58, 346-368. *Skarlicki, D. P., Ellard, J. H., & Kelln, B. R. C. (1998), Third-party perceptions of a layoff: Procedural, derogation, and retributive aspects of justice. Journal of Applied Psychology, 83, 119-127. *Skarlicki, D. P., & Folger, R. (1997). Retaliation in the workplace: The roles of distributive, procedural, and interactional justice. Journal of Applied Psychology, 82, 434-443. *Skarlicki, D. P., Folger, R., & Tesluk, P. (1999). Personality as a mod- erator in the relationship between fairness and retaliation. Academy of Management Journal, 42, 100-108. *Skarlicki, D. P., & Latham, G. P. (1996). Increasing citizenship behavior within a labor union: A test of organizational justice theory. Journal of Applied Psychology, 81, 161-169. *Skarlicki, D. P., & Latham, G. P. (1997). Leadership training in organi- 444 COLQUITT, CONLON, WESSON, PORTER, AND NO zational justice to increase citizenship behavior within a labor union: A replication. Personnel Psychology, 50, 617-633. *Smith, H. J., & Tyler, T. R. (1996). Justice and power: When will justice concerns encourage the advantaged to support policies which redistrib- ute economic resources and the disadvantaged to willingly obey the law? European Journal of Social Psychology, 26, 171-200. *Smith, H. J., Tyler, T. R., Huo, Y. J., Ortiz, D. J., & Lind, E. A. (1998). The self-relevant implications of the group-value model: Group mem- bership, self-worth, and treatment quality. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 34, 470-493. *Smither, J. W., Reilly, R. R., Millsap, R. E., Pearlman, K., & Stoffey, R. W. (1993). Applicant reactions to selection procedures. Personnel Psychology, 46, 49-76. *Spencer, D. G. (1986). Employee voice and employee retention. Academy of Management Journal, 29, 488-502. *Sujak, D. A., Villanova, P., & Daly, J. P. (1995). The effects of drug- testing program characteristics on applicants' attitudes toward potential employment. Journal of Psychology, 129, 401-416. *Summers, T. P., & DeNisi, A. S. (1990). In search of Adams' other: Reexamination of referents used in the evaluation of pay. Human Rela- tions, 43, 497-511. *Sweeney, P. D. (1990). Distributive justice and pay satisfaction: A field test of an equity theory prediction. Journal of Business and Psychol- ogy, 4, 329-341. *Sweeney, P. D., & McFarlin, D. B. (1993). Workers' evaluation of the "ends" and the "means": An examination of four models of distributive and procedural justice. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 55, 23-40. *Sweeney, P. D., & McFarlin, D. B. (1997). Process and outcome: Gender differences in the assessment of justice. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 18, 83-98. *Sweeney, P. D., McFarlin, D. B., & Cotton, J. L. (1991). Locus of control as a moderator of the relationship between perceived influence and procedural justice. Human Relations, 44, 333-342. *Syroit, J., Lodewijkx, H., Franssen, E., & Gerstel, I. (1993). Organiza- tional commitment and satisfaction with work among transferred em- ployees: An application of referent cognitions theory. Social Justice Research, 6, 219-234. *Tansky, J. W. (1993). Justice and organizational citizenship behavior: What is the relationship? Employee Responsibilities and Rights Jour- nal. 6, 195-207. *Tata, J., & Bowes-Sperry, L. (1996). Emphasis on distributive, proce- dural, and interactional justice: Differential perceptions of men and women. Psychological Reports, 79, 1327-1330. *Taylor, M. S., Tracy, K. B., Renard, M. K., Harrison, J. K., & Carroll, S. J. (1995). Due process in performance appraisal: A quasi-experiment in procedural justice. Administrative Science Quarterly, 40, 495-523. *Tepper, B. J., Eisenbach, R. A., Kirby, S. L., & Potter, P. W. (1998). Test of a justice based model of subordinates' resistance to downward influ- ence attempts. Group and Organization Management, 23, 144-160. Thibaut, J., & Walker, L. (1975). Procedural justice: A psychological analysis. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. *Tremblay, M., Sire, B., & Pelchat, A. (1998). A study of the determinants and of the impact of flexibility on employee benefit satisfaction. Human Relations, 51, 667-688. *Truxillo, D. M., & Bauer, T. N. (1999). Applicant reactions to test score banding in entry-level and promotional contexts. Journal of Applied Psychology, 84, 322-339. *Tyler, T. R. (1987). Conditions leading to value-expressive effects in judgments of procedural justice: A test of four models. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 52, 333-344. Tyler, T. R. (1989). The psychology of procedural justice: A test of the group-value model. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 57, 830-838. Tyler, T. R. (1990). Why people obey the law: Procedural justice, legiti- macy, and compliance. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Tyler, T. R. (1994). Psychological models of the justice motive: Anteced- ents of distributive and procedural justice. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 67, 850-863. Tyler, T. R., & Bies, R. J. (1990). Beyond formal procedures: The inter- personal context of procedural justice. In J. S. Carroll (Ed.), Applied social psychology and organizational settings (pp. 77-98). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. *TyIer, T. R., & Caine, A. (1981). The influence of outcomes and proce- dures on satisfaction with formal leaders. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 41, 642-655. *Tyler, T. R., & Degoey, P. (1995). Collective restraint in social dilemmas: Procedural justice and social identification effects on support for author- ities. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 69, 482—497. Tyler, T. R., Degoey, P., & Smith, H. J. (1996). Understanding why the justice of group procedures matters: A test of the psychological dynam- ics of the group-value model. Journal of Personality and Social Psy- chology, 70, 913-930. Tyler, T. R., Lind, E. A., Ohbuchi, K. I., Sugawara, I., & Huo, Y. J. (1998). Conflict with outsiders: Disputing within and across boundaries. Per- sonality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 24, 137-146. *Tyler, T. R., Rasinski, K. A., & McGraw, K. M. (1985). The influence of perceived justice on the endorsement of political leaders. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 15, 700-725. Tyler, T. R., Rasinski, K. A., & Spodick, N. (1985). Influence of voice on satisfaction with leaders: Exploring the meaning of process control. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 48, 72-81. *Van den Bos, K., Lind, F. A., Vermunt, R., & Wilke, H. A. M. (1997). How do I judge my outcome when I do not know the outcome of others? The psychology of the fair process effect. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 72, 1034-1046. *Van den Bos, K., Vermunt, R., & Wilke, H. A. M. (1996). The consis- tency rule and the voice effect: The influence of expectations on proce- dural fairness judgments and performance. European Journal of Social Psychology, 26, 411-428. *Van den Bos, K., Vermunt, R., & Wilke, H. A. M. (1997). Procedural and distributive justice: What is fair depends more on what comes first than on what comes next. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 72, 95-104. *Van den Bos, K., Wilke, H. A. M., & Lind, E. A. (1998). When do we need procedural fairness? The role of trust in authority. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 75, 1449-1458. *Van Dierendonck, D., Schaufeli, W. B., & Buunk, B. P. (1998). The evaluation of an individual burnout intervention program: The role of inequity and social support. Journal of Applied Psychology, 83, 392- 407. *Vecchio, R. P., Griffeth, R. W., & Horn, P. W. (1986). The predictive utility of the vertical dyad linkage approach. Journal of Social Psychol- ogy, 126, 617-625. *Vermunt, R., Blaauw, F., & Lind, E. A. (1998). Fairness evaluations of encounters with police officers and correctional officers. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 28, 1107-1124. Viswesvaran, C., & Ones, D. S. (1995). Theory testing: Combining psy- chometric meta-analysis and structural equations modeling. Personnel Psychology, 48, 865-885. *Wanberg, C. R., Bunce, L. W., & Gavin, M. B. (1999). Perceived fairness of layoffs among individuals who have been laid off: A longitudinal study. Personnel Psychology, 52, 59-84. Wanous, J. P., Sullivan, S. F., & Malinak, J. (1989). The role of judgment calls in meta-analysis. Journal of Applied Psychology, 74, 259-264. META-ANALYTIC REVIEW OF ORGANIZATIONAL JUSTICE 445 *Weaver, G. R., & Conlon, D. E. (1997, August). Explaining broken promises: Timing, justice effects, and behavioral outcomes. Paper pre- sented at the 57th Annual Meeting of the Academy of Management, Boston, MA. *Welbourne, T. M., Balkin, D. B., & Gomez-Mejia, L. R. (1995). Gain- sharing and mutual monitoring: A combined agency-organizational jus- tice interpretation. Academy of Management Journal, 38, 881-899. *Wesolowski, M. A., & Mossholder, K. W. (1997). Relational demography in supervisor-subordinate dyads: Impact on subordinate job satisfaction, burnout, and perceived procedural justice. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 18, 351-362. *White, M. M., Tansky, J. A., & Baik, K. (1995). Linking culture and perceptions of justice: A comparison of students in Virginia and South Korea. Psychological Reports, 77, 1103-1112. Whitener, E. M. (1990). Confusion of confidence intervals and credibility intervals in meta-analysis. Journal of Applied Psychology, 75, 315-321. Williams, L. J., & Anderson, S. E. (1991). Job satisfaction and organiza- tional commitment as predictors of organizational citizenship and in-role behaviors. Journal of Management, 17, 601-617. Received August 23, 1999 Revision received May 12, 2000 Accepted May 15, 2000 Members of Underrepresented Groups: Reviewers for Journal Manuscripts Wanted If you are interested in reviewing manuscripts for APA journals, the APA Publications and Communications Board would like to invite your participation. Manuscript re- viewers are vital to the publications process. As a reviewer, you would gain valuable experience in publishing. The P&C Board is particularly interested in encouraging members of Underrepresented groups to participate more in this process. If you are interested in reviewing manuscripts, please write to Demarie Jackson at the address below. Please note the following important points: • To be selected as a reviewer, you must have published articles in peer-reviewed journals. The experience of publishing provides a reviewer with the basis for preparing a thorough, objective review. • To be selected, it is critical to be a regular reader of the five to six empirical jour- nals that are most central to the area or journal for which you would like to review. Current knowledge of recently published research provides a reviewer with the knowledge base to evaluate a new submission within the context of existing re- search. • To select the appropriate reviewers for each manuscript, the editor needs detailed information. Please include with your letter your vita. In your letter, please iden- tify which APA journal(s) you are interested in, and describe your area of exper- tise. Be as specific as possible. For example, "social psychology" is not suffi- cient—you would need to specify "social cognition" or "attitude change" as well. • Reviewing a manuscript takes time (1-4 hours per manuscript reviewed). If you are selected to review a manuscript, be prepared to invest the necessary time to evaluate the manuscript thoroughly. Write to Demarie Jackson, Journals Office, American Psychological Association, 750 First Street, NE, Washington, DC 20002-4242. work_cxxhkujjyffs5hhkzwuv4igx6m ---- Power, Justice, and the Environment: A Critical Appraisal of the Environmental Justice Movement A 616 VOLUME 114 | NUMBER 10 | October 2006 • Environmental Health Perspectives Power, Justice, and the Environment: A Critical Appraisal of the Environmental Justice Movement Edited by David Naguib Pellow and Robert J. Brulle Cambridge, MA:MIT Press, 2005. 339 pp. ISBN: 0-262-16233-4, $25 Over the past 18 years, hundreds of books have been published on the envi- ronmental justice movement (EJM); however, this is one of the first books to initiate a comprehensive dialogue that cri- tiques strategies, tactics, and discursive frames; examine issues of organizational struc- ture, governance, and resource base; assess goals and outcomes; and pose questions challenging academics and activists to consider where the movement has been and where it may go. The EJM—which emerged in the late 1980s from struggles within communities of color and low-income communities that have been dis- proportionately affected by pollution—is characterized by editors Pellow, an activist–scholar who has published widely on EJ, and Brulle, an associate professor of environmental policy, as “a political response to the deterioration of the conditions of everyday life as society reinforces existing social inequities while exceeding the limits to growth. Thus the EJM laid a foundation for environmental and social justice politics in the twenty-first century.” The heart and strength of these essays by academics, EJ practition- ers, and advocates is the challenge to engage foundational concepts of the EJM that most serious observers and activists have been loath pub- licly to address. Yet 15 years since the historic first People of Color Environmental Leadership Summit, one reads this assessment and analy- sis and wonders why it has taken so long to begin this important inquiry. The editors’ opening chapter succinctly summarizes literature on inequality, social justice movements, and environmental degradation, and presents provocative conclusions. Although Pellow and Brulle note that the EJM has affected the direction of environmental policy, research, and activism and that the EJM has had its “clearest victories” leading local community struggles, they question whether the EJM has achieved its goals and conclude that the “outlook is not positive.” They issue a chal- lenge, echoed by the authors, to the EJM to “complement its well-honed acumen for opposition to unsustainable projects to a concrete vision and plan of action for construction and protection of sustainable com- munities”—a challenge that is being met by many EJ organizations. The collection, targeted to scholars, theorists, practitioners, and activists, has three sections. In the first, “Environmental Quality and Justice: Progress or Retreat?” Bryant and Hockman compare the Civil Rights and EJ movements. Some chapters break the chain of synergy and some authors’ conclusions contradict others, but Benford’s “Half-Life of the Environmental Justice Frame: Innovation, Diffusion, and Stagnation” complements other authors in this book with his provocative argument that the “EJ frame suffers from stagnation as a result of its dif- fuse conceptualization, the many issues it seeks to address, the subordina- tion of environmentalism to human justice, and its failure to embrace and articulate revolutionary solutions.” His argument needs more research and documentation to bolster his conclusion that the EJM’s “power lies in its capacity to disrupt the system rather than to reform it.” Section 2, “New Strategies for Achieving Environmental Justice,” focuses on energy activism, sustainable and just food systems, case stud- ies of collaborative problem solving, and research findings that the gov- ernance structure of EJ groups does not reflect its democracy frame. Brown offers lay-driven efforts to reframe social conceptions of health through the asthma/air quality paradigm, and Targ argues for a state- level comprehensive approach to EJ to address issues and approaches across agency jurisdictions. Pena urges that the EJM advance “explo- ration of autonomy”—self-governance of environmental management in local places—versus the struggle against “toxic racism and its rampant inequalities of place and power.” The third section, “Environmental Justice and the Challenge of Globalization,” highlights South African perspectives, global activism initiatives, and the contrast between the goal of environmental sustain- ability, management of natural resources, and that of the EJM, human justice, wherein the natural environment is important only “inasmuch as it can be seen in terms of human justice.” Brulle and Pellow conclude by advising EJ scholars to balance docu- mentation of problems with a solution orientation, provide a stronger class analysis, and heed more of the links between EJ research and the literature on social movements. They warn EJ activists that forging a national agenda could deprioritize grassroots base building and that the divide between mainstream environmental groups and the EJM must be addressed more productively. They advise EJ groups to build a greater indigenous base of financial support and to appeal to a broader base of the population by addressing its race-based focus to be more inclusive of class, gender, working-class whites, and nation inequalities. This book asks serious questions that have been raised by the EJM itself and continue to challenge its activists. Although this collection can be fascinating, there are some facile recommendations and observations made without sound basis. Nevertheless, this book is a vital addition to the liter- ature, and it catalyzes a critical dialogue on our environmental future. PEGGY SHEPARD Peggy Shepard is co-founder and executive director of West Harlem Environmental Action, founded in 1988 to improve environmental protection, health, and policy in communities of color. She is a member of the National Institute of Environmental Health Sciences Public Interest Liaison Advisory Group, and for- mer chair, U.S. Environmental Protection Agency’s National Environmental Justice Advisory Council. Announcements Book Review Announcements New Books A Theory of General Ethics: Human Relationships, Nature, and the Built Environment Warwick Fox Cambridge, MA:MIT Press, 2006. 400 pp. ISBN: 0-262-06255-0, $68 Analyzing International Environmental Regimes Helmut Breitmeier, Oran R. Young, Michael Zürn Cambridge, MA:MIT Press, 2006. 336 pp. ISBN: 0-262-02602-3, $67 Bilateral Ecopolitics Philippe Le Prestre, Peter Stoett Williston, VT:Ashgate Publishing, 2006. 306 pp. ISBN: 0-7546-4177-5, $99.95 Environmental Health in Central and Eastern Europe K.C. Donnelly, Leslie H. Cizmas, eds. New York:Springer, 2006. 249 pp. ISBN: 1-4020-4844-0, $119.00 Environmental Principles and Ethics Ming H. Wong, Frank W.K. Lee, Martin K.F. Fung Hackensack, NJ:World Scientific Publishing Co., 2006. 240 pp. ISBN: 981-256-838-7, $48 Governing Environmental Flows Gert Spaargaren, Arthur P.J. Mol, Frederick H. Buttel, eds. Cambridge, MA:MIT Press, 2006. 392 pp. ISBN: 0-262-69335-6, $27 Governing Global Desertification: Linking Environmental Degradation, Poverty and Participation Pierre Marc Johnson, Karel Mayrand, and Marc Paquin Williston, VT:Ashgate Publishing, 2006. 312 pp. ISBN: 0-7546-4359-X, $99.95 Noxious New York: The Racial Politics of Urban Health and Environmental Justice Julie Sze Cambridge, MA:MIT Press, 2006. 296 pp. ISBN: 0-262-19554-2, $60 Precautionary Politics: Principle and Practice in Confronting Environmental Risk Kerry H. Whiteside Cambridge, MA:MIT Press, 2006. 208 pp. ISBN: 0-262-23255-3, $50 Sustainability, Civil Society and International Governance John J. Kirton, Peter I. Hajnal Williston, VT:Ashgate Publishing, 2006. 422 pp. ISBN: 0-7546-3884-7, $114.95 The Environment in Asia Pacific Harbours Eric Wolanski New York:Springer, 2006. 497 pp. ISBN: 1-4020-3654-X, $209 A rn o ld G re en w el l/E H P work_czefli22uzhlbi32pc4onk236m ---- Microsoft Word - O'Boyle+with+mcj+editsREVISEDv SOCIAL JUSTICE: ADDRESSING THE AMBIGUITY by Edward J. O’Boyle, Ph.D. Senior Research Associate Mayo Research Institute A somewhat different version of this paper was published in Logos: A Journal of Catholic Thought and Culture, Volume 14, Number 2, Spring 2011. To retrieve the published article, go to www.stthomas.edu/cathstudies/Logos Questions and comments should be directed to: Edward J. O’Boyle, Ph.D. Mayo Research Institute www.mayoresearch.org 1217 Dean Chapel Road, West Monroe, Louisiana 71291 USA Tel: 318/396-5779 E-mail: edoboyle@earthlink.net 2 Social justice is a concept used widely but with different meanings for different users. Fifty years ago Raymond Jancauskas observed that the concept is “vague and ill-defined.” 1 Thirty years later William Waters added that it is “a very helpful but ambiguous term.” 2 Twenty years after Waters’s comment, Rupert Ederer stated that social justice has been reduced to “simply a slogan.” 3 In addition to the different meanings applied to the term, two other sources of ambiguity exist. First, social justice is referred to under at least three other labels: constructive justice, 4 legal justice, 5 and general justice. 6 Second, some ambiguity originates in careless scholarly work. Two examples illustrate this point. In the first instance, Pius XI in his 1937 encyclical Divini redemptoris demonstrates the connection between social justice and the common good. The Vatican website renders that connection in the English version of the encyclical as follows. “Now it is of the very essence of social justice to demand for each individual all that is necessary for the common good” (emphasis added). 7 However, carefully translating the Latin version from the same website into English produces the following. “Now it is of the very essence of social justice to demand from each individual all that is necessary for the common good” (emphasis added). 8 This latter rendering is found in The Encyclicals of a Century 9 where the full text and footnotes of Divini redemptoris are printed and twice in Bernard Dempsey’s influential The Functional Economy. 10 Clearly, “for” indicates a right of the individual whereas “from” signifies a duty. In the second instance, Dempsey attributes the latter rendering correctly to Divini redemptoris in one place 11 but incorrectly to Quadragesimo anno in another. 12 Further, Waters in 3 citing Arnold McKee refers to social justice “in the broad sense” and “in the narrow sense” and recommends McKee to the reader for “an excellent introduction to the subject.” 13 McKee, however, refers to justice -- not social justice -- “in a narrow sense” and “a wide sense.” 14 The line between social justice and social charity is confused and adds to the ambiguity when solidarity is substituted for social charity. Further documenting the various sources of confusion and ambiguity does nothing more than add to these problems. For that reason it makes much more sense to begin with a clear definition of justice and how it applies to economic affairs through three principles: commutative justice, distributive justice, and contributive justice. A clear understanding of these three principles will help remove the ambiguity associated with social justice because, as we intend to demonstrate, all three are necessary for practicing social justice and attaining the common good in that they promote the trust required of human beings in the conduct of everyday economic activities. We will then further clarify charity, social charity and solidarity. Justice Justice is the virtue or good habit of rendering to another that which is owed. This definition closely parallels the version recommended by Aquinas, underscores justice as an obligation or duty and provides additional support for translating the sentence referenced above from Divini Redemptoris as “from each individual.” 15 Having said that, we do well to acknowledge that every duty has a corresponding right. 16 To illustrate, if the buyer has a duty to pay for what he wants or needs, he has a right to that for which he has paid. If the worker has a duty to put in a full day’s work, she has a right to a full day’s pay. Given that the individual has a duty to contribute all that is necessary for the common 4 good and that the common good is served only through such individual contributions, it follows that the individual also has a right to whatever goods are necessary to live in common. Hereafter, we will use “person” instead of “individual” because in mainstream economics “individual,” strictly speaking, encompasses only human individuality, whereas in personalist economics “person” includes both human sociality and human individuality and by definition human sociality is a requirement for living in community. At times social justice is confused with commutative justice and distributive justice. 17 For that reason, it is instructive to turn our attention briefly to those two forms of justice. Commutative justice sets forth the duty of buyer to seller in the marketplace and worker to employer in the workplace. Distributive justice defines the duties of the superior to subordinates whether that interaction takes place in the marketplace or the workplace. However, to understand both types, we must address economic gain. Economic Gain Every exchange involving economic agents who are well-informed and free to act entails gain for the parties involved: What is gotten in the exchange is more highly valued than what is given up. For example, a person shopping for shoes comes across a pair priced at $118. In deciding whether to purchase those shoes that person routinely asks the question, “Are these shoes really worth $118 to me?” If the answer is affirmative, that person purchases the shoes. If the answer is negative, the buyer turns away. If that person is not sure, he or she turns away but may return later to buy the shoes provided they really are worth $118. Economics differentiates between exchange value and use value. Exchange value is what is given up for the good or 5 service acquired through exchange. Use value is what is gotten, that is, the usefulness of the good or service to the person who acquires it. Under competitive market conditions, exchange value should not vary from one person to the next. The price paid for the same dog food in a supermarket is the same for everyone buying that brand of dog food at that store. However, use value is not the same for everyone who buys that dog food because some persons are more deeply attached to their dogs and derive greater pleasure from feeding and caring for them than do others. While exchange value is determined by market conditions at the time and place of the exchange, use value is determined by the value systems of the uniquely different persons involved in the exchange. Exchange value is an objective piece of information. Use value, on the other hand, is a subjective human experience. For every person involved, use value (what is gotten) must be greater than exchange value (what is given up). Without that gain, the exchange cannot be carried out. In the workplace, when the baker hires a sales clerk to tend to customers both parties gain something. The baker gets the clerk’s labor services that are more useful to the baker than the wages that must be paid, thereby adding to the baker’s profits. Without that gain, the baker could not afford to hire the sales clerk. At the same time, the clerk contributes labor services because the wages paid are more useful than the time and effort involved in working. Without that gain, the clerk would not accept the job. In the marketplace, the baker produces more loaves of bread than can be used for personal consumption, and sells them provided what is gotten (the price paid by the customer) is more useful than what is given up (the cost to produce the bread), thereby adding to the baker’s profits. Without that gain, the baker has no incentive to produce and to sell bread. At the same 6 time, the baker’s customer who does not bake bread, or does not make it as well or as inexpensively, buys from the baker because the bread that is gotten is more useful than the money given up. The gain achieved by the consumer can be saved or applied to buying other things that the customer wants or needs. A bargain is an exchange in which the consumer’s gain is greater than initially expected. Commutative Justice Commutative justice states that buyer and seller in the marketplace and worker and employer in the workplace have two duties that are binding on both parties. First, they are to exchange things of equal value. Second, they are to impose equal burdens on one another. Because of this emphasis on equal value and equal burdens, many call commutative justice “equivalence.” Personal experience usually informs us as to what equal value means. By equal burden we mean that the burden of the seller is to give up possession of the good or service in question. For the buyer, the burden is to give up possession of the money necessary to buy and take possession of that good or service. For the worker, the burden is performing the work required by the employer. For the employer, the burden is paying the worker the wage to which they agreed. At first glance, exchanging things of equal value implies that there is no gain involved. On closer examination we see that this is not the case. Exchanging things of equal value means that what is exchanged is of equal exchange value, not equal use value. As we indicated previously, exchange value refers to the price paid to purchase a good or service and the wage or price paid to hire a worker or natural resource to produce that good or service. Use value is what is gotten, that is the usefulness of the good or service or resource to the person who acquires it. 7 There are several specific ways in which commutative justice may be violated in the marketplace: shoplifting, issuing a bad check, loan sharking, and price gouging to name a few. Commutative justice may be violated in the workplace as well: for instance, through expense padding, sweatshops, embezzlement, pilfering and featherbedding. All violate commutative justice either regarding the duty to exchange things of equal value or to impose equal burdens on one another. Distributive Justice Distributive justice defines the duties of the superior to subordinates. In the workplace, distributive justice requires the superior to distribute the benefits and burdens of the group under supervision among its members in some generally equal fashion. This does not mean strictly equal, because significant differences are likely among subordinates, and it is entirely appropriate to consider those differences. For example, handicapped employees may require different parking and restroom accommodations than able-bodied employees. Single parents in general shoulder heavier childcare responsibilities than married parents. Distributive justice demands that the superior differentiate among subordinates only when the differences among them are real and substantial and require different arrangements. A superior may allow a single parent to rush home to tend to a sick child when the same permission might not be given to a married worker with a spouse who routinely stays at home to look after the children. We mention two noteworthy violations of distributive justice: discrimination and kickbacks. Discrimination occurs when the superior differentiates among subordinates for reasons that are insubstantial. In this regard, false stereotyping may be the device used to rationalize the difference in treatment among subordinates. For example, older workers may be 8 treated differently because (according to the stereotyped view held by the employer) they are seen to have “less upside potential” than younger workers. Another form of discrimination would be to treat women differently because according to the false stereotype imposed by the employer work for them is deemed to be of secondary importance in their lives. Favoritism is the other side of the coin of discrimination: treating some better than others for reasons that are superficial or based on the false stereotyping of others. A kickback is the ethical equivalent of a bribe. A bribe is a payment to a superior in the expectation of special treatment. The payment precedes the special treatment. A kickback is a payment for special treatment wherein the payment follows the special treatment. A contractor bribing a provincial highway official in order to influence that official’s decision as to which contractor is to be awarded a construction contract makes payment beforehand. A contractor kicking back to a highway official promises beforehand to make payment after the deal has been closed. Distributive justice has application in the marketplace too, but here the issues are not nearly as serious as in the workplace. In the marketplace, it is the merchant who is the superior because of the obligation to treat customers with fairness. This is done in several ways. A merchant who makes rain checks available is saying in effect that when an item is put on sale at a very favorable price, all customers are treated alike, even those who come to the store after the supply of that item has been exhausted. Under those circumstances, the merchant reorders the item in such quantities to satisfy all customers who have been issued a rain check. “Limit 3 to a customer” tells all customers that everyone is entitled to purchase no more than three of a specific item on sale so that one customer will not buy the entire available supply. “Sale price 9 effective as long as supplies last” tells customers when the item is put on sale that customers who delay in coming to the store may be disappointed in finding that the item has been sold out. The key to understanding all such practices is that while the specific terms of sale differ, once a specific practice is put in place there is no difference in the way those terms are applied, no matter the customer. This meets the merchant’s obligations under distributive justice. Further, though some customers may not be able to take advantage of the favorable opportunities afforded by the merchant (for any number of reasons including lack of transportation, being away at the time of the sale, or inability to travel to the store), the merchant’s duties under distributive justice extend only to those who actually enter the store. The merchant must have made an effort to properly inform customers of sale opportunities and to maintain the usual store operating hours. Contributive Justice Contributive justice asserts that insofar as a person receives benefits from a group, that person has a duty to maintain and support the group. Paying dues -- a duty -- is the usual requirement for the persons joining and remaining active in a membership organization. Failure to pay membership dues typically reduces a person to inactive membership status enjoying fewer benefits. as compared to those in good standing. Of the three principles of economic justice, contributive justice is least familiar to Americans, because many Americans think first and foremost in terms of human individuality and have a high regard for “rugged individualism.” For that reason, we have only weak examples of common expressions for contributive justice in the workplace and the marketplace. 10 In the workplace, where employees commonly work in groups or teams, expressions such as “doing my fair share,” “pulling my load,” and “paying my dues” are common. There are even greater problems in seeing contributive justice faithfully practiced in the marketplace. Even so, there are certain expectations when persons come together whether for a concert, ball game, or to enter a flow of traffic. The newest arrival in a ticket line or traffic line is expected to wait his turn and not cut into the line. To do otherwise is disrespectful of those who have been waiting and sets an example for others to do the same in which case pushing, shoving, and cutting off other cars may become the rule rather than the exception. A general loss of civility may follow that is destructive to our sense of community. When it comes to violations of contributive justice, however, the marketplace and the workplace offer several powerful examples. In the workplace, industrial spying and sabotage violate contributive justice because the person who appears to be a loyal and productive member of one business establishment actually is faithful to a rival organization and seeks to undermine the effectiveness of the first establishment by stealing secrets and by disrupting its work. Is it a violation to hire a person from a rival establishment and pick her brain for whatever information she might be able to share with the new employer? It is if that person surrenders proprietary information, information to which the former employer can claim a clear property right (such as a secret formula for making a product). Other prominent examples of violations of contributive justice would include computer tampering, tax evasion, 18 product tampering, and insider trading. Limits on Economic Gain Limits on the amount of economic gain are necessary to prevent one party from taking advantage of another and to assure that market exchange serves everyone fairly and effectively. 11 Those limits derive from the duties that economic agents owe one another under commutative justice, distributive justice, and contributive justice. Commutative justice limits ill-gotten or excessive gain because what is gotten and what is given up in the exchange are what were freely and openly agreed to before the exchange took place. For example, the ill-gotten gain for the employer who operates a sweatshop is the added profits from denying workers what is due them. The ill-gotten gain for the employee who embezzles is money that rightfully belongs to the employer. Distributive justice limits ill-gotten gain because the superior assures that what is gotten and what is given up are the same for everyone in the same or similar circumstances. To illustrate, the ill-gotten gain for the employer who pays some workers less than others for the same work is the added profits gotten through discrimination. The ill-gotten gain for the public official who has been bribed to award a contract for a clearly substandard proposal is the money which that official has gotten dishonestly. Contributive justice limits excessive gain because each member gives up (contributes) what is necessary to maintain the group provided what is gotten by that member is the same or similar to what is gotten by other members of the group. The ill-gotten gain for the inside trader comes at the expense of persons who sell shares that the inside trader knows are undervalued or who buy shares that the insider knows are overvalued. The ill-gotten gain in industrial spying is the property that rightfully belongs to someone else. Social Justice The emphasis in contributive justice on the duty of the member to the group and the duty of the person under social justice to contribute to the common good suggest that social justice 12 and contributive justice are identical. Dempsey holds this view and asserts that Heinrich Pesch does too. 19 And apparently, Benedict XVI holds this view as well. 20 However, before addressing social justice further, we insist that contributive justice, while it can be described and examined separately from commutative justice and distributive justice, cannot be separated in the actions of a truly just person. In economic affairs a person cannot serve justice without being faithful to all three at once. Recall for a moment the language of Divini redemptoris. “Now it is of the very essence of social justice to demand from each individual all that is necessary for the common good.” 21 As stated previously, if a person has a duty to contribute all that is necessary for the common good he also has a right to whatever goods are necessary to live in common. Trust is one of the goods necessary to live in common and trust is maintained only through the faithful practice of commutative justice and distributive justice in addition to contributive justice. Benedict XVI states unequivocally that today trust “has ceased to exist” in the market economy. 22 Simply put, commutative justice, distributive justice, and contributive justice are a package deal. Practicing social justice means practicing all three. Thus, at all times and in all places, social justice requires precisely this: all that is necessary for the common good. Living in common means living in a complex network of intertwined communities: family, workplace, neighborhood, church, civic organization, trade association, city, province, nation-state, all nations. Each one brings different duties and different rights, and those duties and rights vary depending on the condition of the person in areas such as health, economic means, and so on. Moreover, the duties and rights are not of the same significance. To illustrate, 13 relationships of care within a family are more significant than the duties and rights of membership in a civic organization. Acknowledging our participation in these networks illuminates two points. First, a person has a duty to contribute to whatever elements he or she belongs to, say family, workplace, and nation-state, and a corresponding right to whatever goods are produced in common by those elements. Second, more comprehensive elements in the social order have a duty according to the principle of subsidiarity not to interfere in the production of less comprehensive elements and to help those less comprehensive elements produce more effectively. Thus the goods produced in common should be produced by the smallest element possible in order to position production as close as possible to the family and its members so as to better assure that the goods produced in common are available to meet the needs of human beings as persons and to contribute to their proper development. In this scheme a strong preference for action is taken first by private organizations and then by public agencies but only after those agencies have offered assistance and those private organizations still are not operating effectively. Put differently, the common good does not always require goods produced by public agencies. For this kind of decentralized, bottom-up social organization to produce effectively, trust is necessary across a network of communities that as we already observed requires the faithful practice of commutative justice, distributive justice, and contributive justice, the three constituent parts of social justice. Social justice and subsidiarity work together toward the common good 14 that includes the production of the goods necessary to live in common as well as the moral good through which the dignity of the human person is respected. Two examples help to demonstrate the connection between social justice and subsidiarity. If cities in general are capable of dealing with the sanitation needs of the community, the persons living in those cities have a duty to pay the taxes or fees to support municipal sanitation systems and a right to access those systems. The provincial or federal government has no justification for taking over municipal sanitation systems provided the cities are operating those systems effectively, though the provincial or federal government might be of assistance by offering grants to upgrade wastewater treatment facilities. In this example, the common good is served by the production of public goods at the local level. Public education at the elementary and secondary levels for years has been largely a local matter though often with financial assistance from both state and federal government and subject to court-ordered desegregation. In some instances, states have taken over control when a school has failed in its primary instructional mission. Even so, there are no examples of direct and total federal takeover; rather reform more often has placed control of failing schools in the hands of other officials through the establishment of charter schools and has allowed parents to remove their children from failed schools by granting vouchers to make attending private schools more affordable. In this example, there is a public consensus, perhaps not as strong as years ago, that the common good is served by locating and retaining control of public education principally at the local level. From its beginnings in the 1930s, the basic design and management of unemployment insurance have been a state government responsibility. Though some persons and organizations 15 at that time urged making UI a federal program, the arrangement allowed each state to customize UI to its own unique economic conditions and the values of its employers and workers regarding the needs to be met through UI benefits and the burdens to be shouldered through UI taxes. From time to time, it has been necessary for the federal government to intervene when too many of the unemployed were exhausting their benefits and states could not bear the full cost of paying extended benefits from their depleted trust funds. These interventions have been restricted to financial support. They never have involved a federal takeover of a state program even in the most recent recession where benefits have been extended beyond the usual 26 weeks payable by the states to 99 weeks payable by the federal government. In this example, the common good is served by keeping control of programs of aid to the unemployed mainly at the state level. Needs, Charity, Social Charity, Solidarity Common needs are needs that are “common to all members of the community” (emphasis added). 23 Accordingly, the common good involves providing for those common needs. Citing Gaudium et spes, Benedict in Caritas in veritate puts it this way: “Beside the good of the individual, there is a good that is linked to living in society: the common good. It is the good of ‘all of us,’ made up of individuals, families and intermediate groups who together constitute society.” 24 Even so, not all human needs are common needs. Since each human being is unique, each has needs and wants that strictly speaking are personal and satisfied by specific goods. (We will shortly take up the difference between needs and wants.) Dempsey calls these goods elementary goods. 25 As a personalist espousing an economics in which the economic agent is represented as a person, we prefer to call them personal goods. 16 Accepting subsidiarity as a governing organizational principle, it follows that the common good is served first by private goods and then by public goods as necessary. By demanding “all that is necessary for the common good,” social justice is served at times by public goods but preferentially by private goods. Two key problems remain. What should be done when the economic system does not produce all that is necessary for the common good? What should be done when it does not produce all of the necessary personal goods? The first is a problem of production, the second a problem of distribution. The production problem requires an ongoing public discourse on the very structure of our economic institutions, especially the role of private enterprises vs. public agencies in the process of production. The solution might lie in public agencies offering private enterprises assistance to produce the goods necessary to serve the common good. Or, it might involve public agencies taking on a more aggressive regulatory role. It might extend to direct government control of private enterprises, ownership of those enterprises or both. Alternatively, it could involve deregulation and privatization in order to free private enterprises from a government sector that has grown too large to be effective. Subsidiarity can be helpful in this discourse. Even so, the discourse can run on for years as it has in the United States regarding the health care system In an economy such as the United States that produces goods of all kinds in abundance, an insufficiency of personal goods is not a production problem, nor is it a social justice problem. It is instead a distribution problem, a problem of insufficiency or poverty. As so ably demonstrated by the likes of Blessed Mother Teresa and her community of nuns, relieving this insufficiency often is prompted by the theological virtue of charity “by which we love God 17 above all things for his own sake, and our neighbor as ourselves for the love of God.” 26 At the same time, the natural virtue of caring infused with the conviction that every human being is precious motivates many others to alleviate the very same insufficiency. The use of the term social charity creates additional confusion because that term is ambiguous. Does it refer to the theological virtue of charity or the natural virtue of caring? We take up that question after the following two comments on poverty that may help us sort through some of the ambiguity regarding social justice. As noted previously, it is important to differentiate human needs from human wants. Poverty is an issue of unmet human needs such as food and clothing. It is not a matter of unsatisfied human wants such as vacations and luxury cars. Subsidiarity plays a role here just as we observed in the case of social justice. Intervention by private organizations such as faith-based neighborhood groups that provide assistance to persons and families with unmet personal needs is preferred when and if they are positioned closer to those seeking assistance and therefore are better able to differentiate between an unmet need and an unsatisfied want and to identify a false claim for assistance. We turn next to the meaning of solidarity and how it relates to charity. In Rerum novarum, 27 Pope Leo XIII referred to the family as “part of the commonwealth” and made clear that Christians are expected to help any family in need as “a duty, not of justice (save in extreme cases), but of Christian charity -- a duty not enforced by human law.” 28 Here the Holy Father clearly means the theological virtue. According to Ederer, the term “social charity” originated in section 88 of Quadragesimo anno. 29 By this, Pope Pius XI meant neither the theological virtue nor caring. Rather, the 18 Pontiff’s intent was to identify it with solidarity. To underscore this important point, Ederer asserts that the concept of solidarity was developed at length by Pope John Paul II in Sollicitudo rei socialis and identified with social charity in Centesimus annus. 30 In Sollicitudo rei socialis John Paul says that there is a “growing awareness of interdependence among individuals and nations,” a transformation that is acquiring a moral connotation . . . . When interdependence becomes recognized in this way, the correlative response as a moral and social attitude, as a “virtue,” is solidarity. This then is not a feeling of vague compassion or shallow distress at the misfortunes of so many people, both near and far. On the contrary, it is a firm and persevering determination to commit oneself to the common good; that is to say to the good of all and of each individual, because we are all really responsible for all. This determination is based on the solid conviction that what is hindering full development is [the] desire for profit and [the] thirst for power . . . 31 And shortly thereafter, he continues: it has been possible to identify many points of contact between solidarity and charity, which is the distinguishing mark of Christ’s disciples. In the light of faith, solidarity seeks to go beyond itself, to take on the specifically Christian dimension of total gratuity, forgiveness and reconciliation. One’s neighbor is then not only a human being with his or her own rights and a fundamental equality with everyone else, but becomes the living image of God the Father, redeemed by the blood of Jesus Christ and placed under the permanent action of the Holy Spirit. One’s neighbor must therefore be loved, even if an enemy, with the same 19 love with which the Lord loves him or her; and for that person’s sake one must be ready for sacrifice, even the ultimate one: to lay down one’s life for the brethren. 32 Support for Ederer’s claims are found in Centesimus annus. In this way what we nowadays call the principle of solidarity, the validity of which both in the internal order of each nation and in the international order I have discussed in the Encyclical Sollicitudo rei socialis, is clearly seen to be one of the fundamental principles of the Christian view of social and political organization. This principle is frequently stated by Pope Leo XIII, who uses the term “friendship,” a concept already found in Greek philosophy. Pope Pius XI refers to it with the equally meaningful term “social charity.” Pope Paul VI, expanding the concept to cover the many modern aspects of the social question, speaks of a “civilization of love.” 33 In Caritas in veritate, Benedict employs “solidarity” frequently and attributes it to John Paul. 34 He does not use the term “social charity.” He uses “social justice” only once by which he apparently and unfortunately, for purposes of the present argument, means contributive justice. 35 Even so, Benedict offers the following insight to clarify the difference between justice and solidarity both of which are directed toward the common good. In the global era, economic activity cannot prescind from gratuitousness, which fosters and disseminates solidarity and responsibility for justice and the common good among different economic players. It is clearly a specific and profound form of economic democracy. Solidarity is first and foremost a sense of responsibility on the part of everyone with regard to everyone, and it cannot therefore be merely 20 delegated to the State. While in the past it was possible to argue that justice had to come first and gratuitousness could follow afterwards, as a complement, today it is clear that without gratuitousness, there can be no justice in the first place. What is needed, therefore, is a market that permits the free operations, in conditions of equality opportunity, of enterprises in pursuit of different institutional ends. Alongside profit-oriented private enterprise and the various types of public enterprise, there must be room for commercial entities based on mutualist principles and pursuing social ends to take root and express themselves. It is from their reciprocal encounter in the marketplace that one may expect hybrid forms of commercial behaviour to emerge, and hence an attentiveness to ways of civilizing the economy. Charity in truth, in this case, requires that shape and structure be given to those types of economic initiative which, without rejecting profit, aim at a higher goal than the mere logic of the exchange of equivalents, of profit as an end in itself. 36 Benedict also calls attention to the close linkage between subsidiarity and solidarity: “the former without the latter gives way to social privatism, while the latter without the former gives way to paternalist social assistance that is demeaning to those in need.” 37 Three general comments regarding profits and Catholic social thought must be added here. First, a commercial enterprise operating in a market system requires profits as a condition of survival. Nothing in Catholic social thought can or should force the owners of a failed enterprise to continue operating at a loss. Second, profits earned honestly through faithful compliance with the demands of the three principles of economic justice are the “stuff” that 21 makes gratuitousness possible. Catholic social thought can and should remind Catholics and others often and with conviction that profits are not an end in themselves, that they are to be freely shared with others. Third, Catholic social though can and should boldly inform economics that its insistence on teaching the profit maximization principle and that profits are the sole objective of a commercial enterprise in a market system are directly at odds with gratuitousness that is necessary for justice, solidarity, and the common good. 39 Final Remarks We began this article with the purpose of reducing the ambiguity surrounding social justice. We have argued that practicing social justice means practicing all three types of justice relevant to economic affairs: commutative justice, distributive justice, and contributive justice. All three are necessary for the common good, because all three foster the trust required for human beings to carry out their everyday economic activities in common. To some, as Ederer warns, social justice is just a slogan. 38 Whatever ambiguities remain, we have argued that social justice is indeed not a mere slogan. Living in common means living in a network of communities. Subsidiarity helps us decide where in that network responsibility for production should be located. The goods produced in common should be produced by the smallest element in the network in order to locate production as close as possible to the family and its members; this assures that such goods are available to meet the needs of human beings as persons and to contribute to their proper development. The principle of subsidiarity requires that preferential action be taken first by private organizations and then by public agencies but only after public agencies have offered assistance 22 and only if private organizations still are not operating effectively. Thus, the common good does not always require goods produced by public agencies. The problem with justice is that it results in a condition where no one owes anything to anyone else, a condition that James Schall describes as an “isolated hell.” 40 John Paul puts it this way: “justice, if separated from merciful love, becomes cold and cutting.” 41 In other words, the faithful practice of social justice coupled with subsidiarity removes the sources of dysfunction that prevent human beings from living successfully in community. However, social justice and subsidiarity do not by themselves establish a functional community. Christians practice the theological virtue of charity to address the burdens of persons with unmet personal needs. If those needs are not addressed, and they plainly are not under social justice, the poor are marginalized and effectively excluded from living in common. And where Christians practice charity, persons of good will may practice the natural virtue of caring. Benedict and John Paul warn that more is needed to preserve the dignity of the human person than a form of social justice enlightened by subsidiarity and the theological virtue of charity focused narrowly on one’s immediate neighbors. They are not sufficient for a truly functional community that exists in an increasingly interdependent “economic, cultural, political, and religious” order. Rather, the full development of the human person depends on solidarity -- “a firm and persevering determination to commit oneself to the common good . . . the good of all and of each individual.” 42 Benedict says that without the gratuitousness that makes solidarity possible, “there can be no justice in the first place.” 43 We conclude that the functional community depends on charity or caring to meet the needs of the poor, gratuitousness that makes possible social justice that 23 combines commutative, distributive, and contributive justice and removes human barriers to community when coupled with subsidiarity, and finally, solidarity -- a deep and abiding personal commitment to the common good. Notes 1. Raymond Jancauskas, “The Concept of Social Justice: Some Current Applications,” Review of Social Economy 17 (1959): 34. 2. William Waters, “Evolution of Social Economics in America,” in Social Economics: Retrospect and Prospect, ed. Mark A. Lutz (Boston: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1989), 113. 3. Rupert Ederer, “A Principle for Economics,” The Catholic Social Science Review 13 (2008): 114. 4. Waters, Evolution, 95. 5. Bernard Dempsey, The Functional Economy: The Bases of Economic Organization, (Englewood-Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1958), 165; Waters, Evolution,113. 6. Arnold McKee, “What is “Distributive Justice?” Review of Social Economy 39 (1981): 3; Waters, Evolution, 113. 7. Pius XI, Divini redemptoris, 1937, English text, http://vatican.va/holy_father/pius_xi/encyclicals/documents/hf_pxi_enc_19031937_ divini- redemptoris_en.html (26 Jun. 2009), § 51. This flawed rendering also is found on the Eternal Word Television Network website, http://www.ewtn.com/library/encyc/p11divin.htm. We made no attempt to look for it at other sites. 24 8. “Atqui socialis justitiae est id omne ab singulis exigere, quod ad commune bonum necessarium sit” (emphasis mine). Pius XI, Divini redemptoris, 1937, Latin text, http://vatican.va/holy_father/pius_xi/encyclicals/documents/hf_p-xi_enc_19031937 _divini-redemptoris_lt.html (30 Jun. 2009), § 51. The author is grateful to John Czyzynski, SCJ, for help in translating the Latin text correctly into English. 9. Encyclicals of a Century, (Derby NY: Daughters of St. Paul, Apostolate of the Press, 1942), 314. 10. Dempsey, Functional Economy, 220, 372. 11. Ibid., 372. 12. Ibid., 220. Perhaps what accounts for this lapse is that Dempsey on the same page (202) states that in the language employed in Quadragesimo anno (§57, §58) Pius XI says in effect that “the practical application of the virtue of social justice . . . is equated with the common good.” 13. Waters, Evolution,113. 14. McKee, “Distributive Justice,” 2–3. 15. Dempsey, Functional Economy,164. 16. Waters, Evolution, 95, correctly asserts that a just society is one in which the rights of the individual and the community are satisfied. 17. Ibid., 113. 18. Tax avoidance is an entirely different matter. Avoidance means arranging one’s income in a way that conforms to the tax code but reduces the amount owed in taxes. 19. Dempsey, Functional Economy, 370, 372. 25 20. Benedict XVI, Caritas in veritate, 2009, http://vatican.va/holy_father/benedict_xvi/encyclicals/documents/hf_ben-xvi_enc_ 20090629_caritas-in-veritate_en.html (8 Jul. 2009), § 35. 21. Pius XI, Divini redemptoris, English text (corrected), § 51, emphasis added. 22. Benedict XVI, Caritas in veritate, § 35. 23. Dempsey, Functional Economy, 272–73. 24. Benedict XVI, Caritas in veritate, § 7; quote marks in the original. 25. Dempsey, Functional Economy, 272. 26. Catechism of the Catholic Church, (San Francisco, CA: Ignatius Press, 1994), § 822. 27. Leo XIII, Rerum novarum, 1891, http://vatican.va/holy_father/leo_xiii/encyclicals/documents/hf_l-xiii_enc_ 15051891_rerum- novarum_en.html (9 Jul. 2009), § 14. 28. Ibid., § 22. 29. Ederer, “A Principle,” 107. 30. Ibid., 114. 31. John Paul II, Sollicitudo rei socialis, 1987, http://vatican.va/holy_father/john_paul_ii/encyclicals/documents/hf_jp-ii_enc_ 30121987_sollicitudo-rei-socialis_en.html (10 Jul. 2009), § 38. 32. Ibid., § 40. 33. John Paul II, Centesimus annus, 1991, http://vatican.va/holy_father/john_paul_ii/encyclicals/documents/hf_jp-ii_enc_ 01051991_centesimus-annus_en.html (10 Jul. 2009), § 10. 26 34. Benedict XVI, Caritas in veritate, § 38. 35. Ibid., § 35. 36. Benedict XVI, Caritas in veritate, § 38; emphasis in the original. Later Benedict adds “international solidarity,” “social solidarity,” and “welfare solidarity” (see § 60) without clarifying how those terms differ from “solidarity” as defined in this section. The difference seems to somehow relate to the principle of subsidiarity. It is also important to note in this passage that, in the early 1900s, for example, the German Jesuit economist Heinrich Pesch identified the two as complements: “charity must complement justice so that one person will help the other, even when he is not compelled to do so by any kind of legal obligation.” See Heinrich Pesch, Heinrich Pesch on Solidarist Economics: Excerpts from the Lehrbuch der Nationalokonomie, trans. Rupert J. Ederer (Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1998), l77. 37. Benedict XVI, Caritas in veritate, § 58. 38. Ederer, “A Principle,” 114. 39. The profit maximization principle asserts that profits of the typical firm are maximized at the unique combination of price and output where the additional cost of producing one more unit of output is equal to the added revenue from selling that unit. 40. James Schall, “Justice: The Most Terrible of the Virtues,” Journal of Markets and Morality 7 (2004): 412. 41. John Paul II, “From the Justice of Each Comes Peace for All,” 1998, http://vatican.va/holy_father/john_paul_ii/messages/peace/docoments/hf_jp-ii_mes_ 08121997_xxxi-world-day-of-peace_en.html (10 Jul. 2009): 1. 27 42. John Paul II, Sollicitudo rei socialis, § 38. 43. Benedict XVI, Caritas in veritate, § 38. work_czqbf67jhbcbzhjc43euknpfgu ---- 1 (Not) talking about justice: justice self-recognition and the integration of energy and environmental-social justice into renewable energy siting Ian Bailey a * and Hoayda Darkal a a School of Geography, Earth and Environmental Sciences, University of Plymouth, Drake Circus, Plymouth, UK  Corresponding author. Email: ian.bailey@plymouth.ac.uk 2 Abstract Renewable energy often provokes heated debate on climate change, energy security, and the local impacts of developments. However, how far such discussions involve thorough and inclusive debate on the energy and environmental-social justice issues associated with renewable energy siting remains ambiguous, particularly where government agendas prioritise renewable energy and planning systems offer limited opportunities for public debate on value-based arguments for and against renewable energy developments. Using the concept of justice self-recognition, we argue for greater attention to public discussion of the justice dimensions of renewable energy to assist in developing mechanisms to integrate distributive and procedural fairness principles into renewable energy decision-making. To explore how justice is currently invoked in such contexts, we examine recent UK policies for renewable energy and public submissions to applications for small-scale wind energy projects in Cornwall, UK. The analysis of public comments revealed that justice concerns were rarely discussed explicitly. Comments instead did not raise concerns as justice issues or focused implicitly on distributive justice, stressing local aesthetic, community and economic impacts, clean energy and climate change. However, the findings indicated limited discussion of procedural or participatory justice, an absence that hampers the establishment of coherent procedures for deciding acceptable impacts, information standards, public participation and arbitrating disputes. We conclude by suggesting procedural reforms to policy and planning to enable greater public expression of justice concerns and debate on how to negotiate tensions between energy and environmental- social justice in renewable energy siting decisions. Keywords: wind energy; energy and environmental-social justice; justice self-recognition; planning policy; Cornwall 3 Introduction Recent years have seen burgeoning interest in energy justice as a lens for identifying and addressing inequities within energy production and supply systems (Goldthau and Sovacool 2012; Heffron, McCauley and Sovacool 2015; Jenkins et al. 2016; McCauley et al. 2013; Sovacool and Dworkin 2014). Few would dispute the fundamental ambition of energy justice to promote universal access to reliable, safe, affordable and sustainable energy (McCauley et al. 2013), but implementing its ideals can provoke controversy where energy decisions impinge on other societal justice concerns. A prime example is where policies to promote renewable energy conflict with community concerns to protect themselves from the negative health, environmental or social impacts of energy developments (Cotton 2017; Malin and DeMaster 2016; Wolsink 2007). Local resistance to renewable energy is still commonly attributed to a “NIMBY” (Not In My Back Yard) mindset underpinned by self- interest (Bidwell 2013). However, numerous commentators have critiqued use of the term by developers and decision-makers to disregard local concerns about unfair burdens, inadequate consultation, and other forms of environmental-social injustice 1 (Bailey 2016; Devine-Wright 2011a; 2012; Gross 2007). Community perceptions of justice have accordingly formed a major theme in research on renewable energy siting (Gross 2007; Jobert et al. 2007; Langer et al. 2016). Some studies have explored normative frameworks for achieving just and inclusive decision- making, employing concepts such as participatory planning and landscape justice (Gross 2007; Howard 2015; Mason and Milbourne 2014), while others have explored community evaluations of distributive and procedural justice within decisions on energy infrastructure siting (e.g. Anderson 2013; Armeni 2016; Bidwell 2013; Cotton and Devine-Wright 2011; Delicado et al. 2014; Langer et al. 2016; Ottinger et al. 2014; Simcock 2016; Zoellner et al. 2008). However, most studies have used retrospective techniques, such as surveys, interviews or focus-group techniques, that arguably prompt participants to reflect on justice issues they may not otherwise have considered or raised in planning debates, and which often attract those with stronger opinions who may not reflect broader community views. Delicado et al (2014) and Cowell’s (2010) studies of attitudes to wind power in Portugal and Wales partly avoid these problems by combining interviews with reviews of public responses to planning consultations. However, Delicado et al. (2014) analysed comments on environmental impact assessments conducted prior to planning applications while 4 Cowell (2010) examined responses to a strategic search for acceptable areas for wind energy rather than specific wind farm applications. Importantly, neither examined how communities and individuals expressed justice arguments for and against wind energy at the point when decisions on planning permission were being made. Gaining more reliable understandings of how energy and local environmental-social justice are perceived and articulated by groups affected by renewable energy siting – and how conflicts are managed – requires greater attention to public discussions during “live” planning debates, when the impacts of proposals become apparent and directly pertinent to residents. Research consistently shows higher public support for renewable energy at an abstract level compared with actual deployments (Bidwell 2013; Wolsink 2007; Zoellner et al. 2008) and that people use different logics – often stressing technology characteristics, place attachment and procedural flaws (Devine-Wright 2012) – to justify opposition. However, how justice is debated in its unedited forms during planning processes remains under-researched. This gap also represents a priority because of the difficulties in achieving equitable accommodations between energy and environmental-social justice without open and inclusive dialogue about how these should be balanced in energy siting. Such dialogue may help to counter the temptation for government and developers to see renewable energy as advantageous to national and commercial goals and opposition as parochial and NIMBYist (Fuller and McCauley 2016). Equally, it may encourage greater reflection by residents on justice arguments favouring renewable energy in specific locations. This article seeks to fill this research gap by examining recent experiences with wind energy siting in Cornwall, an area of the UK that has experienced a surge in small-scale wind schemes since 2010. Wind energy was chosen as a focus because wind turbines remain controversial on the grounds of visual, landscape, health and wildlife impacts (West et al. 2010; Wolsink 2007), so one would anticipate strident debate on justice issues during planning applications. The first main strand of enquiry examines how energy and environmental-social justice have been constructed in recent UK national policies governing planning applications for wind energy. Although the Department for Communities and Local Government’s (DCLG) 2012 National Planning Policy Framework and supporting policies for renewables do not refer directly to energy or environmental-social justice, they project clear ethical agendas that stress the responsibility of all communities to contribute to energy security and reducing emissions (DCLG 2012). The second strand focuses on how public 5 views were expressed in written submissions to 14 planning applications for wind turbine projects in Cornwall, to examine how supporters and objectors have invoked justice issues. Our main argument is that selective interpretations of energy and environmental- social justice by central government – both in terms of issues and the priority given to national agendas compared with local considerations – combined with an inability and/or reluctance by communities to discuss wind energy projects as justice issues has contributed to a lack of robust debate on the justice dimensions of wind energy siting. Politically motivated interpretations of “fair” outcomes have instead dominated, driving, first, planning policy heavily weighted towards approving applications – sometimes reversing local decisions – and, latterly, conditions where approval has become difficult even where only minority objections exist. In exploring the implications of this situation, the article seeks to advance understanding of the contested relationship between energy justice and other forms of environmental-social justice while drawing attention to the need for energy policy in countries like the UK to pay greater attention to enabling inclusive and open dialogue on the justice dimensions of renewable energy siting. The next section explores key energy and environmental-social justice principles and debates affecting renewable energy decisions, focusing particularly on procedural and participatory justice within decision-making (Jenkins et al. 2016). We then interrogate recent UK policies for small-scale renewables and how government interpretations of justice have influenced decision-making on wind turbine applications in Cornwall. Following this, the methods for analysing public submissions on turbine applications and the study’s findings are discussed. Finally, we explore the study’s implications and ways to encourage greater consideration of the diverse and multi-scalar justice issues affected by renewable energy decision-making. Energy and environmental-social justice: principles and tensions The range of socio-environmental concerns debated under the banner of environmental justice has diversified appreciably in recent decades (Schlosberg 2004; 2007; Walker 2009). Interest has particularly centred on climate and energy justice as lenses for analysing inequities associated with climate change and the demands of energy security, access and environmental sustainability that make up the energy trilemma (Cotton and Devine-Wright 2012; Hall 2013; Heffron et al. 2015; Jenkins et al. 2014; 2016). While this proliferation 6 reflects the multiple ways socio-environmental issues are entangled with questions of fairness, it has undoubtedly heightened the complexity of the environmental justice landscape (Klinsky and Dowlatabadi 2009; Sovacool 2014). Climate, energy and environmental justice share similar philosophies about fairness in the allocation of rights and responsibilities (Jenkins et al. 2016; Sovacool 2014), but their different foci make it problematic to assume a neat alignment of goals. Our main interest here is intersections between energy justice and local environmental-social justice, because although climate justice forms a general backcloth to energy policy, energy and environmental-social justice often compete more directly with each other in renewable energy siting disputes. McCauley et al. (2013) defines energy justice as the promotion of universal access to safe, affordable and sustainable energy. As such, its agenda extends beyond revealing where and why energy injustices occur to incorporate a normative focus on reducing injustices in energy systems (Jenkins et al. 2016). Environmental justice, meanwhile, centres on meaningful public involvement in environmental decision-making and non-discriminatory protection from environmental risks, particularly for marginalised and disadvantaged groups (Bullard and Johnson 2000; Walker and Bulkeley 2006), and thus articulates more multi- faceted concerns for social and environmental equity in relation to energy and the collateral effects of energy decisions. Tensions between these concepts may emerge where actions to address energy injustices encroach on other justice priorities, creating ambiguity in the definition of fair outcomes depending on whether energy or environmental-social justice lenses are applied, the relative importance given to local, national or international concerns, and how short- and long-term impacts are prioritised. For example, where arguments about mitigating climate change by reducing fossil fuel dependency clash with concerns for aesthetic, social and environmental quality in areas targeted by low-carbon energy projects, questions about national energy production become ensnared in local debates about how burdens and benefits should be allocated (Bailey 2016; Langer et al. 2016). Conversely, such debates may be circumscribed by the power relations affecting how different justice arguments are prioritised. Climate change and energy security are often regarded as national and international concerns, so without appropriate checks and balances may overshadow local justice concerns. While, Jonas and Gibbs (2010) indeed argue that recent years have seen the rise of a distinctive low-carbon polity in the UK that has exposed sub-national political 7 arenas to uncompromising new values, political agendas, and forms of state regulation. They contend that such domination has subverted broader readings of sustainable development while promoting socially uneven re-workings of state-society relations, a phenomenon Swyngedouw (2010: 214) regards as symptomatic of a post-political approach to climate governance in which: “technocratic management and consensual policy-making has sutured the spaces of democratic politics.” Negotiating tensions between energy and environmental-social justice requires close attention not only to distributive justice but also to the procedures for encouraging stakeholder participation and adjudicating between competing viewpoints (Haggett 2011; Langer et al. 2016; Rowe and Frewer 2004; Schlosberg 2004; Walker 2009; Walker and Day 2012). Distributive justice focuses on social and spatial equity in the effects of energy decisions to tackle existing inequalities and avoid new inequities. Procedural justice, meanwhile, focuses on promoting stakeholder participation to utilise local knowledge and democratise decision-making, trustworthy assessment of the effects of decisions, and evidence-led decision procedures (Gross 2007; MaCoun 2005; Sovacool et al. 2013; Jenkins et al. 2016). Rowe and Frewer (2004) additionally stress the need for clear criteria for evaluating the effectiveness of participation, but also note the difficulties in achieving clear and objective definitions of effectiveness. In value-laden debates on renewable energy siting, effective participation can carry various meanings but relates generally to ensuring all legitimate viewpoints are considered in relation to some combination of their merits and whether they represent the wider views of those affected by siting decisions (Armeni 2016; McClymont and O’Hare 2008). In this context, Schlosberg (2007) and Heffron et al. (2015) also emphasise the importance of recognition justice in guarding against the use of stereotypes or other means of cultural domination that might undermine the rights of individuals and groups to participate in consultations. Space constraints prevent discussion of all the distributive, procedural and recognition justice issues affecting renewable energy siting. However, two issues stand out as especially pertinent to the present discussion. The first, already noted, concerns the need for multi-issue and multi-scalar perspectives on justice to protect against energy concerns overshadowing other issues, the domination of national and international agendas, or the derailing of policy by local opposition. Although some definitions of energy justice incorporate concern for how the burdens and benefits of energy systems are distributed 8 (Bickerstaff et al. 2013; Sovacool 2014), how far these include the full range of non-energy impacts from energy choices remains ambiguous and narrower interpretations may give primacy to renewable energy on climate or other grounds while giving lesser weight to local socio-environmental impacts based on the reasoning that energy transitions cannot be entirely free from detrimental impacts. Counteracting such tendencies requires consistency, transparency and accountability in decision-making, not least because of the longevity of energy infrastructure and the potential for procedural flaws to erode trust in decision-makers (Sovacool et al. 2016). However, despite agreement that achieving just outcomes is seriously compromised without procedural safeguards, Maguire and Lind (2003) and Skitka et al. (2003) warn that procedural fairness cannot guarantee acceptance of decisions; groups strongly opposed to wind farms may care more about outcomes and be more inclined to “cry foul” if decisions go against them, while supporters may find little fault with the same procedures because of convictions about wind energy (Gross 2007). The contingent and outcome-dependent nature of procedural justice reinforces the importance of robust participation that recognises different viewpoints (Schlosberg 2007; Young 2000). As Bulkeley, Edwards and Fuller (2014: 33) note, just climate and energy outcomes require: “nuanced engagement with how… action creates both costs and benefits, which are unevenly experienced… it involves engaging substantively with the notion of justice as recognition”. Recognition justice has been discussed extensively in relation to racial, cultural, gender and socio-economic discrimination (Jenkins et al. 2016; McCauley et al. 2013; Sovacool and Dworkin 2014), but renewable energy debates also possess their own pejoratives, such as the labelling of objectors as “NIMBYs”, wind turbines as environmentally or economically inefficient, and supporters as unscrupulous profiteers with little regard for affected communities (Devine-Wright 2011a; Wolsink 2007). Most discussions of recognition justice have focused on marginalised groups and minority viewpoints. However, a less frequently discussed issue is that of justice “self- recognition”, a term we use to encapsulate two interlinked ideas: participants’ awareness that their opinions represent legitimate fairness issues rather than just personal viewpoints; and their ability and confidence to utilise the vocabulary of justice to defend their rights during renewable energy conflicts. Justice self-recognition, we argue, forms a vital part of recognition justice because recognition by individuals that their concerns raise legitimate distributive or procedural issues is a pre-requisite of petitioning for them to be treated as 9 such by decision-makers. Conversely, where perceived injustices are not expressed in justice language, the greater the likelihood of them being seen as less important by decision-makers regardless of the merits of the arguments, particularly where they are minority viewpoints. Although Honneth (2004) again warns of participation being skewed by the influence and “noisiness” of actors rather than the ethics of arguments or the worthiness of groups, justice self-recognition represents an under-researched aspect of efforts to address trade-offs between energy justice and other spheres of economic and social life (Fuller and McCauley 2016). We discuss justice self-recognition further later in the article but, before this, the next section reviews recent UK policies on small-scale renewables and the energy-justice agendas created by these policies. Feed-in tariffs, planning policy and Cornwall’s renewables boom Cornwall’s engagement with renewable energy began in 1991 with the construction of the UK’s first commercial on-shore wind farm near the village of Delabole. Over the next decade six further wind farms were built in Cornwall, but since 2010 the region has experienced a surge in small-scale onshore wind and solar generation. Between 2010 and 2016, the number of turbines installed or approved grew from around 100 to 421, while 91 commercial solar-PV sites have also been constructed (Cornwall Council 2016a; 2016b). The first main factor driving this expansion was the introduction in 2010 of the UK feed-in tariff (FiT) by the Labour government. This scheme offered premium prices for renewable energy projects up to 5MW capacity, with tariffs differentiated by: technology; electricity consumed at the point of generation or exported; project size (smaller schemes receive higher tariffs); and installation date (Ofgem 2016). In keeping with the ethos of FiTs and other traditions in UK energy policy, the scheme provided a regulatory framework and financial incentives but left market forces and the planning system to determine where and in what forms investment should occur (Mitchell 2008). The second driver, the introduction of the 2012 National Planning Policy Framework (NPPF) by the Coalition government, took a more assertive approach towards the conditions under which developments should be approved. At the core of the NPPF was a presumption in favour of sustainable development, which the DCLG (2012: 4) argued: “should be seen as a golden thread running through both plan-making and decision-taking”. The ministerial 10 foreword included an contentious definition of sustainable development: “Development means growth.” (ibid: i), while Section 14 argued that local authorities should approve developments unless “adverse impacts… would significantly and demonstrably outweigh the benefits, when assessed against the policies in this Framework” (ibid: 4). The DCLG’s Planning practice guidance for renewable and low carbon energy (PPGRLCE), published in 2013, further articulated the government’s ethical agenda on renewables, stating that all communities had a responsibility to contribute to energy from renewable and low-carbon sources and that local planning authorities should develop positive strategies for renewable energy (DCLG 2013). The NPPF instructed planning authorities not to require applicants to demonstrate the overall need for renewable energy and to recognise that even small-scale projects made a valuable contribution to cutting greenhouse-gas emissions, and directed planning committees to approve applications “if impacts are (or can be made) acceptable” (DCLG 2012: 23; 2013). Although both documents acknowledged that green energy should not override environmental or community concerns, except for noise and essential safety measures, most criteria were only specified qualitatively for interpretation by local authorities, consultative agencies (e.g. Natural England), and/or developers (DCLG 2013). Several aspects of the justice agendas created by these policies merit further discussion. The first concerns the government’s use of “hard” and “soft” governing technologies to regulate the expectations and actions of local planning authorities (Rose- Redwood 2006). “Soft” discursive power was exercised by projecting ethical norms that prioritised national concerns for energy supplies, cutting greenhouse gas emissions, and investment; correspondingly, the role of planning was to deliver renewable energy infrastructure where impacts could be made acceptable, rather than emphasising autonomy or local priorities (Murdoch 2004). “Hard” material power was exerted by specifying “positive criteria” under which applications should be approved (DCLG 2013). Additionally, limiting the grounds for rejecting applications also restricted the capacity of communities to challenge government interpretations of renewable energy policy. Equally, though the PPGRLCE required attention to cumulative impacts, it imposed no quantitative and few area-based restrictions on renewable energy. A further element of material power was the retention of final decision-making power if local institutions resisted government agendas (McKee 2009) under provisions in UK planning law allowing applicants to appeal rejected 11 projects to the Planning Inspectorate for further assessment against the NPPF, local plans and the project’s characteristics. Its decisions can only be revoked through legal proceedings. Finally, the introduction of interventionist strategies alongside the FiT enabled commercial actors to become influential interpreters of the government’s energy agenda (Catney et al. 2014). In essence, the policies gave developers strong incentives to promise landowners lucrative returns for investing in renewable energy and powerful arguments to press for the approval of projects (Bailey 2016). But how have local communities responded to this agenda, what arguments have been used to support or object to applications, and to what extent have communities articulated distributive and procedural justice arguments during planning debates on renewable energy? The next section begins to address these questions by explaining the methods used to examine public submissions to wind turbine applications in Cornwall. Methods Research into the use of justice arguments by affected communities consisted of analysis of public submissions on 14 wind turbine applications submitted between 2011 and 2015. Submissions to planning websites were preferred to observing public meetings after attending three meetings because each meeting was dominated by vocal objectors and involved hostile exchanges that may have deterred the expression of some viewpoints. In contrast, planning websites allow anonymous online or postal submissions, so involvement is not limited by internet restrictions or concerns about ill feeling, and longitudinal sampling of planning decisions was possible. It was anticipated that people with stronger opinions would be more likely to submit comments, potentially biasing the sample, but this would be likely with any research method. The sample included three applications approved by planning committees, six that were approved on appeal, and five where appeals were dismissed. This led to an overall dataset of 842 submissions and 14 applications proved sufficient to achieve saturation in the arguments used by both supporters and objectors 2 . Additionally, capturing arguments for applications with different outcomes gave confidence of having achieved a representative sample of how different arguments – including appeals for justice and fairness – were expressed in submissions. 12 Supporters and objectors’ arguments were analysed to explore four main themes: (1) The main issues raised, for example: visual and landscape disturbance; noise and other health effects; business benefits and negative impacts; ecology and heritage; community effects; distribution of benefits; property values; cumulative impacts; consultation procedures; and climate change and energy security. (2) The spatial emphasis of arguments, classified into local, regional, national or international issues, to identify any patterns in the geographical scale at which supporters and objectors pitched arguments. (3) The extent to which justice arguments featured in submissions, using a three-level analysis: (i) where arguments used terms like “justice”, “unjust”, “fair” or “unfair”; (ii) where references to justice could be inferred but justice terminology was not employed; and (iii) where no evidence existed that notions of (un)fairness were consciously expressed by the individual. (4) Although not all arguments made direct or indirect reference to justice issues, content analysis enabled tracing of all arguments to some form of fairness/unfairness claim. Arguments were consequently linked to outcome, distributive and procedural justice, then procedural justice arguments were further sub-divided into: (i) decision-making rules (e.g. the NPPF or local plans); (ii) assessment procedures; and (iii) consultation processes (Ottinger, Hargrave and Hopson 2014; Schlosberg 2007). In so doing, we investigated how frequently each justice category was invoked to analyse how different justice ideas influenced the way arguments were presented. The crucial advantage of textual analysis was that it examined arguments as they were expressed by individuals and considered by decision-makers, and thus avoided prompted reflections on the justice dimensions of arguments. Conversely, the technique relied on interpretation of whether individuals expressed their arguments as justice issues and the 13 forms of (un)fairness being asserted. Although interpretation was mostly straightforward (see points 1-4 above and the relevant results sections for explanations of the criteria used to classify the presence or absence of justice arguments, and types of justice arguments identified), a selection of arguments was read independently by both researchers to reduce misinterpretation. Additionally, the analysis could not determine whether individual arguments influenced the approval or rejection of applications because public submissions formed only part of the evidence base for decision-making. However, because the intention was to explore how justice arguments were used rather than whether they influenced decisions, this did not impose significant limitations. Contesting wind turbine applications Key issues and spatial emphases The first phase of analysis revealed a familiar range of issues being raised about wind energy (Table 1) (Cowell 2010; Delicado et al. 2014; Devine-Wright 2011a; Gross 2007; Zoellner et al. 2008). Among objectors, three main categories of impact were stressed: effects on rural landscapes, including visual and landscape impacts, the cumulative effects of multiple turbines, and impacts on wildlife and heritage (48.3% of objections); effects on people (health and noise, community, damage to tourism, declining property values, and uneven distribution of financial benefits) (31.1%); and criticisms of decision-making, such as government policies supporting ineffective and/or expensive technologies, and unsatisfactory consultation or assessment (17.1%). Supporters’ comments, meanwhile, focused on the benefits of wind power (clean energy, combating climate change, energy security and future generations (43.2% of arguments)); local economic benefits (24%); and the limited negative impacts of turbines (30.4%); while a further 2.4% criticised objectors as selfish and short-sighted. Although these results largely corroborate previous studies, one noteworthy tendency was for supporters to submit short general commentaries supporting wind energy, whereas many objectors provided detailed analyses of government policy, planning requirements, impact assessments, or specific impacts. This provides an initial indication of power relations in the planning process: supporters appeared to feel little need to offer elaborate arguments because of the NPPF’s support for wind energy, whereas objectors instinctively 14 or consciously identified that a detailed evidence base spanning multiple technical and planning issues was required to convince decision-makers that the application failed to meet the government’s acceptability requirements (Usher 2013). Table 1: Main Issues Raised by Supporters and Objectors (n=842) Supporters (n=134) Objectors (n=708) Issue % Main spatial emphasis Issue % Main spatial emphasis Clean energy 28.0 Global/ national Landscape and visual impacts 28.2 Local, regional Aesthetically pleasant 15.2 Local Health and noise 13.3 Local Temporary/limited impacts 15.2 Local, regional Cumulative impacts 10.3 Local, regional Farm livelihoods 12.8 Local Business/tourism impacts 8.9 Local, regional Local economic benefits 11.2 Local Ineffective technology 7.6 National, global Climate change 6.4 Global Wildlife 6.5 Local Energy security 6.4 Local, national, global Consultation 6.5 Local Selfish/short-sighted objectors 2.4 Local Community/personal effects 5.3 Local Future generations 2.4 Global Distribution of benefits 3.6 Local Heritage 3.3 Local, regional Flawed assessment 3.0 Local Other, including procedure 3.5 Local, regional, national 100.0 100.0 15 Further distinctions emerged in the spatial framing of objectors and supporters’ arguments. Table 2 indicates that although both groups primarily discussed local effects, opponents concentrated almost entirely on local issues, while 32.3% of supporters’ arguments also stressed national and international issues like energy security and climate change. The general accent on local issues would appear to reflect a desire by both camps to invoke a sense of local identity that conveyed ideas of community, landscape and heritage preservation (objectors) or livelihoods and enhanced local distinctiveness (supporters) to gain traction with local planning committees (Usher 2013; Devine-Wright 2011b). However, the greater emphasis among supporters on national and international issues might correspondingly reflect attempts to remind committees of the requirements of the NPPF 3 , particularly when interwoven with broader ethical arguments. As one supporter wrote, “there is a moral obligation to cut emissions. Unless we cut electricity, we need turbines for the sake of future generations”. Combative reasoning emphasising regional and local issues were also used by objectors to challenge the ethics of policies they regarded as creating unequal burdens and benefits, and by supporters to question the reasoning of objectors. As one objector argued, “the turbine brings zero benefits to local populace. The views of the environmental Nazis should not be allowed to cow the rest of us to silence”, while another noted that a proposed turbine: condemns people to a huge impact on turnover and likely profitability to help one business. Don't harm so many people, businesses, homes and tourists’ destinations for one developer who only cares about his relatively small financial gain and disregards the wider loss to the community, both residential and commercially. Supporters argued conversely that a turbine would: “contribute to the county becoming energy self-sufficient” and attacked objectors as: “short sighted to oppose the turbines. Who would want to live near a nuclear reactor?” offering an interesting, if speculative, choice between different forms of energy generation. 16 Table 2: Spatial scale of justice arguments Totals % Supporters Objectors Total Supporters Objectors Total Local 80 560 640 52.6 81.2 76.0 Regional 23 79 102 15.1 11.4 12.1 National 24 47 71 15.8 6.8 8.4 Global 25 4 29 16.5 0.6 3.5 152 690 842 100.0 100.0 100.0 Justice and public debate on turbine applications The next phase of analysis examined the ways discussion of justice featured in public comments. To recap, all submissions were first analysed to identify whether commentators referred directly or implicitly to energy or environmental-social justice, or whether there was no evidence of the individual framing arguments as justice issues. Further content analysis was then used to explore links between each argument and elements of outcome, distributive or procedural justice, even where these were not expressed in such terms. Predictably, given the controversial nature of turbine siting, all arguments had justice connotations, though many were inferred rather than declared and relied on researcher interpretation. Its main purpose, therefore, was to illuminate the emphasis on outcome, distributive or procedural justice within submissions rather than intent. Surprisingly given the strength of community views on distributive and procedural justice reported in the literature (e.g. Armeni 2016; Bidwell 2013; Delicado et al. 2014; Simcock 2016; Zoellner et al. 2008), only 4.8% of arguments referred openly to justice ideas. For example, one objector described the decision process as “undemocratic and manifestly unfair when government policy is supposed to give local people a greater say”. Another claimed that “it is clearly unfair I should have a turbine on my boundary, making it impossible for me to carry on my business”. A further 15% referred to justice issues without using justice terminology (e.g. “I will have a serious loss of living amenity”), but 80.2% of arguments made neither direct nor indirect reference to justice issues even where 17 cumulative impacts were raised (e.g. “the many other turbines and solar developments in the area will detrimentally affect tourism”, “Cornwall has met its targets for renewable energy” and “renewable energy is the future”). Most arguments were instead presented as “verifiable” statements rather than as outcome, distributive or procedural justice claims. To probe public discussion of justice concerns further, the final stage of analysis traced links between each argument and elements of outcome, distributive or procedural justice even where they were not expressed in justice terms. Arguments were linked to outcome justice where they focused on the overall merits of wind energy as a response to climate change, energy security and/or economic regeneration, and to distributive justice where they commented on the distribution of impacts and benefits. Procedural justice was then divided into three components: (1) assessment issues, e.g. methods for evaluating impacts, or the conclusions of impact studies; (2) participation, e.g. lack of consultation, representation, or impact of public opinions on decisions; or (3) procedural issues, e.g. criticisms of policies and planning procedures for determining applications. Unsurprisingly, distributive justice formed the dominant theme (65.2% of arguments), reflecting concerns that turbine owners and other parts of the country would benefit from developments while most disadvantages would be experienced by nearby residents (Figure 1). As one respondent noted, “local people would have the regular insulting reminder of the injustice, in the form of subsidies for the back pockets of the landowner and developer”. In contrast, only 19.1% of arguments related to overall outcome fairness, mostly by supporters. Arguments here included: Fossil fuels are running out rapidly, so we need renewable energy to protect energy security. Global warming affects farming and humanity. The majority agree with renewable energy as a way of meeting the country's energy requirements. However, some opponents’ arguments also linked to outcome justice where they questioned the wisdom of wind energy: 18 There is a central misconception that wind turbines are a solution to climate change, brought about by collaboration between the greedy energy industry and aimless government policies. Wind turbines are not economic or helping to reduce carbon footprints These are inefficient taxpayer subsidised machines. Figure 1: Types of justice arguments in consultation submissions Procedural justice issues were predictably dominated by objectors but, surprisingly given the controversial elements of government policy, featured in just 15.7% of arguments. 5.8% of total arguments related to assessment procedures, 5.7% to participation, and 4.2% to the rules for determining applications. Common assessment complaints included one objector who claimed that “there were errors in the noise assessment, properties were missed from the evaluation, and the assessment of visual impacts was entirely subjective”, while criticisms about consultation included: We were provided with no information about the application, making a mockery of the consultation process. 19 The people living near the site object, yet we have to contend with anonymous people supporting applications that do not identify their locations. Finally, several submissions were critical of local and national government policy: The Council has no strategy for wind turbines and the application is inconsistent with local plans. The process is undemocratic and manifestly unfair. Recent changes in government policy and the Localism Act are meant to give local people a greater say. Our village has suffered under recent political and economic policies; we have lost our school and public house. Now government policy is undermining the community and driving divisions between residents. The low overall use of justice arguments, particularly procedural justice, among the submissions nevertheless contrasts starkly with other studies that indicate strong community views on the justice dimensions of renewable energy siting (Anderson 2013; Armeni 2016; Bidwell 2013; Cotton and Devine-Wright 2011; Delicado et al. 2014; Langer et al. 2016; Ottinger et al. 2014; Simcock 2016; Zoellner et al. 2008). Lack of public awareness of connections between wind energy and justice seems unlikely given the findings of previous studies and the instances where procedural or other issues were expressed vociferously. Limited public understanding of technical assessments (e.g. noise, landscape visual impact, and heritage) may have contributed to lack of discussion of assessment concerns, though some submissions provided detailed critiques while others demonstrated awareness of planning policy (e.g. “there needs to be legislation on minimum distances from buildings” and: “the Localism Act says developments should not be permitted if the local community objects” 4 ). A more plausible explanation for the deficit is that respondents recognised that challenging the values or provisions of government policies increased the risk of submissions being disregarded as emotive and unimportant. Supporters and opponents instead sought to influence decisions by emphasising technical or planning requirements. For objectors, this encouraged an accent on local identities and distributional considerations that were recognised in national policy and local plans, whereas supporters had greater scope to air general opinions that reflected the government’s views on 20 renewable energy. In both cases, but more obviously for objectors, the normative agendas established in the NPPF inhibited people’s confidence to utilise justice concepts and language to support viewpoints even where they felt government policies were distributively or procedurally unfair. The inconsistency with previous research almost certainly stems from the methods used to explore public opinions on the justice dimensions of wind energy (see Cowell 2010; Haggett 2011; Howard 2015). Usher’s (2013) analysis of a coalmine application in Yorkshire similarly reveals how activist groups adapted to planning protocols by adopting a professionalised lexicon that emphasised planning and technical objections because they believed emotive arguments would be discounted (also Cass and Walker 2009). In this case, opposition groups secured the rejection of the coalmine by stressing the protection of attractive landscapes within greenbelt land and other material planning considerations that maximised their chances of the planning committee’s decision being upheld by the Planning Inspectorate in the event of an appeal. Similarly, objectors to the wind turbine applications reviewed appeared to recognise that contesting the fairness of government policies would prove unproductive and sought instead to influence decision-making within the existing rules of planning policy. Summing up, it appears that the choice of data collection methods can significantly alter the understandings gained about how energy and environmental-social justice are debated and influence planning decisions. This and Usher’s study both analysed textual evidence from “live” decision-making processes rather than relying on prompted accounts of the fairness of decision-making on wind energy developments (though see Delicado et al. (2014) for a partial exception). The latter approach advances general understandings of how community perceive justice and trust in decision-making on energy siting but may provide less trustworthy insights on people’s ability and confidence to express justice as a concern during decision-making itself. A greater emphasis on investigations that directly probe how justice issues are discussed during energy siting disputes thus appears to be crucial in gaining a deeper understanding of how power relations shape the discussion of energy and environmental-social justice in renewable energy decision-making. 21 Concluding discussion Disputes over the siting of renewable energy developments are ultimately debates about justice: in the distribution of benefits and burdens; in the mechanisms used to promote public participation; and in the procedures used to evaluate information and arbitrate between competing viewpoints. The deficits in public discussion of the justice issues associated with wind energy siting identified in this study, combined with the strong community opinions on distributive and procedural justice in previous research (e.g. Bidwell 2013; Cowell 2010; Delicado et al. 2014; Howard 2015; Langer et al. 2016; Ottinger et al. 2014; Simcock 2016; Zoellner et al. 2008), raises important concerns about the UK government’s commitment to public debate on the justice implications of renewable energy. In particular, strong government agendas and “technical rationalist” leanings within planning processes (Cass and Walker 2009; Usher 2013: 821) appear to have eroded the ability and confidence of affected communities to express concerns as justice issues, even where they regarded outcomes or procedures as unfair. Although this generally favoured supporters, objectors and supporters both sought to gain influence by linking arguments to government agendas (e.g. climate change, energy security and localism) or government- determined planning considerations (e.g. landscape impact and noise requirements) rather engaging in open-ended debate about how to balance broader-scale energy justice and local environmental-social justice (Armeni 2016; Usher 2013). This policy approach, we argue, marginalised an important source of accountability (Catney et al. 2014; Rose-Redwood 2006) and may prove counterproductive to the government’s long-term aims to decarbonise the UK’s energy system if it erodes public trust and compounds local resistance to renewable energy (Wolsink 2007; Ottinger, Hargrave and Hopson 2014). Indeed, such tensions already appear to have affected UK policies for wind energy. The Conservative Party’s 2015 election manifesto acknowledged that although onshore wind was making a meaningful contribution to the UK’s energy mix: “Onshore windfarms often fail to win public support… and are unable by themselves to provide the firm capacity that a stable energy system requires. We will end any new public subsidy for them and change the law so that local people have the final say on windfarm applications” (Conservative Party 2015: 57). This pledge was fulfilled in June 2015, when the Secretary of State issued guidance instructing planning authorities only to approve new onshore wind projects if “the development site is in an area identified as suitable for wind energy 22 development in a local and neighbourhood plan”; and/or where, “following consultation, it can be demonstrated that the planning impacts identified by affected local communities have been fully addressed and therefore the proposal has their backing” (Hansard 2015). Although this decision theoretically gave communities a greater voice in planning, wind energy supporters have criticised the decision for creating new biases and inconsistency in the acceptance criteria applied to applications submitted before and after the statement (RenewableUK 2015) 5 . Reflecting on efforts to inject greater democratisation into debates on the justice dimensions of energy transitions, Healy and Barry (2017: 453) argue that addressing climate change and energy security requires radical changes to energy systems and that “a just transformation of the socio-energy system is a decision to live in a different type of society” (original emphasis). They nevertheless stress that justice-led decision-making must address the conflict-laden ethics, politics and power dynamics of energy (Jenkins et al. 2017) to guard against Machiavellian approaches to energy transition and the treatment of rural areas as energy sacrifice zones (Hernández 2015; Kelly-Reif and Wing 2016). We argue that this necessitates renewed efforts to make energy policy and planning systems amenable to public justice self-recognition and discussion of the distributive and procedural justice implications of energy transitions and the adoption a multi-issue and multi-scalar approach which prioritises procedural fairness in how competing conceptualisations of energy and environmental-social justice and national and local priorities are mediated in policy and planning. First, it entails greater commitments within national policy to managing the value choices presented by renewable energy through discussion rather than imposed agendas that constrain engagement and treat community concerns as a hurdle to be overcome (Cass and Walker 2009; Healy and Barry 2017). Second, it implies readjusting planning policy to place greater emphasis on guaranteeing procedural fairness and consistency in the formulation of local-level justice and acceptability principles for energy projects, and the creation of mechanisms for encouraging all parties to deliberate on the justice issues raised by developments and to facilitate negotiated approaches to arbitrating energy and environmental-social justice conflicts in affected areas (Chilvers 2008; Dietz and Stern 2008). One possibility, similar to that advocated by Tingey et al. (2017), would be to introduce a statutory duty for all local authorities to develop negotiated low-carbon plans. They report that although 311 out of 434 UK local authorities had produced energy and low- 23 carbon plans by early 2017, significant variations existed in their detail and emphasis on “energy” compared with “low-carbon” (which may not include renewables), technologies, and the methods for developing plans (Tingey et al. 2017). Alongside strengthening commitments to planned approaches to renewable energy, the NPPF and planning guidance could “justice- and democracy-proof” plans by replacing normative statements with commitments to local negotiation on when projects should be approved, including identifying issues local authorities must consider during negotiations. These might include: separation distances between properties and different types and sizes of renewables; impacts on landscape character, heritage assets and ecology; shadow flicker; criteria for cumulative impacts; and benefit sharing for communities and affected properties. Also integral to this approach would be balancing technical assessments with expectations for participatory planning and other deliberative techniques to encourage wide-ranging input into negotiating criteria for determining proposals (Cass and Walker 2009). Although locally negotiated energy plans may ease some fear-related barriers to public justice self-recognition and debate on the justice dimensions of renewable energy, further action would be required to facilitate discussion of individual applications. Planning officers currently produce committee reports recommending whether to approve applications based on the officer’s interpretation of national policy, the project’s characteristics and representations received. Although committees are not obliged accept officers’ recommendations, they must specify reasons for rejection and reports form an important part of the evidence base for appeals. One way to diffuse excessive influence by individual officers would be to require planners to produce neutral issues discussion documents rather than recommendations explaining to residents and other stakeholders the impact and justice criteria adopted in negotiated plans and arrangements provided for discussing projects. Feedback on discussion documents, again collected through participatory planning, would then provide a key document for decision-making. In so doing, planning officers would seek to promote constructive dialogue by reporting repeated arguments by residents as material justice issues to be considered against negotiated energy plans rather than, as Cass and Walker (2009) observed, dismissing them as self- interested, irrational and unwelcome intrusions into “rational” planning processes (McClymont and O'Hare 2008). 24 This article has sought to contribute new insights on public engagement with energy and environmental-social justice and the integration of justice issues into debates on renewable energy by drawing attention to deficits in the use of justice arguments by residents during wind energy conflicts in Cornwall. The small number of applications examined limits the scope for more than tentative generalisation and suggestions for fostering greater discussion of linkages between justice and wind energy. However, the contrast with previous studies that indicate strong community views on distributive and procedural fairness in wind energy decision-making (e.g. Bidwell 2013; Zoellner et al. 2008) highlights a need for greater investigation of how justice ideas are invoked and influence energy decision-making in “live” planning debates to improve understandings of the political and social factors influencing the mediation of energy and local environmental-social justice and national and local priorities. Surveys and interviews provide useful indicators of individuals’ reflective interpretations of distributive and procedural fairness but need to be supplemented by greater use of investigative techniques, such as analysis of public comments on planning applications and observing planning meetings, that directly probe people’s confidence to express justice concerns at the sharp end of decision-making. The evidence from this study certainly suggests that a significant gap exists between the two and a need for further research on mechanisms for encouraging and empowering open-ended debate on the justice dimensions of renewable energy Revising policy and planning to enable greater public debate on the justice dimensions of wind energy siting would almost certainly make renewable energy policy more contested. However, like Cass and Walker (2009: 68), we question whether discussion of values such as justice is undesirable if it enables: “productive forms of engagement… in which multi- directional and open dialogue between all parties is enabled and in which the emotions of public responses are acknowledged and respected as a necessary part of debating what is at stake.” This does not imply that justice arguments should become a vehicle for legitimating existing views. Rather, debating justice implies challenging preconceptions and finding points of accommodation within policy frameworks that place primary emphasis on procedural fairness to encourage trust-based dialogue on distributive and procedural fairness in energy siting debates. The challenge of designing decision-making and consultation procedures that increase people’s confidence and ability to contest unfair treatment is also not limited to wind 25 energy. Similar issues have dogged UK experiences with hydraulic fracturing for shale gas extraction where, in May 2016, the government overturned local authority refusal to grant an operating licence at Preston New Road, Lancashire, despite 18,022 objections compared with 217 expressions of support. Similarly, in December 2016 the high court ruled in favour of fracking at Kirby Misperton, North Yorkshire, where objectors outnumbered supporters by 4,300 to 36 (Kechagia 2017). In both instances, objectors vented frustration at the use of governing powers to support applications but have so far failed to reverse what Cotton (2017: 185) describes as “inherent contradictions of environmental justice in the… Government’s localist and planning reform agendas”. Reforming governance processes to enable public discussion of the justice dimensions of energy transitions, and placing procedural fairness at the heart of reforms to give public opinion genuine impact, seem both reasonable and judicious. The thornier question is whether governments are willing to open energy agendas to values as well as “rational” planning considerations. Some of the opinions might prove inconvenient for achieving rapid energy transitions, but a more inclusive approach would help to prevent energy policy being dominated by agenda-driven interpretations of energy and environmental-social justice. Notes 1 We use the term “environmental-social justice” to capture the fact that many issues positioned within environmental justice framings extend beyond environmental burdens to include wider social issues affected by energy and environmental policies (Walker, 2009). 2 Standard letters produced by applicants or agents were excluded to prevent distortion of the dataset. In one example, 162 of 208 submissions were standard letters supporting the application, mostly from people living outside Cornwall. 3 Although it is unlikely that supporters deliberately emphasised national and international issues to influence appeals, planning inspectors are required to assess applications against 26 the NPPF and may give less weight to local arguments that fall outside material planning considerations. 4 Under the Localism Act 2011, the government committed to devolving more decision- making powers to local authorities and to enabling local people to have a genuine say over issues affecting their area (DCLG, 2011). 5 Even the implications of DCLG guidance remain uncertain at the time of writing. In late 2016, the Secretary of State allowed an appeal in Cornwall arguing that, objections notwithstanding, the proposal indicated that the scheme’s impacts are, or can be, made acceptable and therefore can be deemed to have the backing of the affected local community (emphasis added) (DCLG, 2016). 27 References Anderson, C. 2013. The networked minority: how a small group prevailed in a local windfarm conflict. Energy Policy, 58, 97-108. Armeni, C., 2016. Participation in environmental decision-making: reflecting on planning and community benefits for major wind farms. Journal of Environmental Law, 28 (3), 415–441. Bailey, I., 2016. Renewable energy, neoliberal governance and the tragedy of the Cornish commons. Area, 48 (1), 119–121. Bickerstaff, K., Walker, G., and Bulkeley, H., eds, 2013. Energy justice in a changing climate: social equity and low-carbon energy. London: Zed Books. Bidwell, D. 2013. The roles of values in public beliefs and attitudes towards commercial wind energy. Energy Policy, 58, 189-199. Bulkeley, H., Edwards, G., and Fuller, S., 2014. Contesting climate justice in the city: examining politics and practice in urban climate change experiments. Global Environmental Change, 25, 31–40. Bullard, R.D., and Johnson, G.S., 2000. Environmentalism and public policy: environmental justice: grassroots activism and its impact on public policy decision making. Journal of Social Issues, 56 (3), 555–578. Cass, N., and Walker, G. 2009. Emotion and rationality: The characterisation and evaluation of opposition to renewable energy projects. Emotion, Space and Society, 2 (1): 62–69. Catney, P., et al., 2014. Big society, little justice? Community renewable energy and the politics of localism. Local Environment: The International Journal of Justice and Sustainability, 19 (7), 715–730. Chilvers, J., 2008. Deliberating competence: theoretical and practitioner perspectives on effective participatory appraisal practice. Science, Technology and Human Values, 33 (2), 155–185. Conservative Party, 2015. The Conservative Party Manifesto 2015 [online]. Available from: https://www.bond.org.uk/data/files/Blog/ConservativeManifesto2015.pdf [Accessed 15 June 2017]. https://www.bond.org.uk/data/files/Blog/ConservativeManifesto2015.pdf 28 Cornwall Council, 2016a. Operational Wind Turbines/Wind Farms 1/9/16 [online], Available from: http://www.cornwall.gov.uk/media/6012192/wind-turbine-operational.pdf [Accessed 2 September 2016]. Cornwall Council, 2016b. PV Applications 1/9/16 [online]. Available from: http://www.cornwall.gov.uk/media/6011305/PV-sites-applications-larger-sites.pdf [Accessed 2 September 2016]. Cotton, M., 2017. Fair fracking? Ethics and environmental justice in United Kingdom shale gas policy and planning. Local Environment, 22 (2), 185–202. Cotton, M. and Devine-Wright, P. 2011. Discourses of energy infrastructure development: a Q-method study of electricity transmission line siting in the UK. Environment and Planning A, 43 (4), 942-960. Cotton, M., and Devine-Wright, P., 2012. Making electricity networks “visible”: industry actor constructions of “publics” and public engagement in infrastructure planning. Public Understanding of Science, 21 (1), 17–35. Cowell, R. 2010. Wind power, landscape and strategic, spatial planning–the construction of ‘acceptable locations’ in Wales. Land Use Policy, 27 (2), 222-232. DCLG, 2011. A plain English guide to the Localism Act. London: DCLG. DCLG, 2012. National planning policy framework. London: DCLG. DCLG, 2013. Planning practice guidance for renewable and low carbon energy. London: DCLG. DCLG, 2016. Town and Country Planning Act 1990 – Section 78: appeal made by XXX, land at XXX: application Ref: XXX. London: DCLG. Delicado, A., et al. 2014. Not in anyone’s backyard? Civil society attitudes towards wind power at the national and local levels in Portugal. Science and Technology Studies, 2 (2), 49- 71. Devine-Wright, P., 2011a. Public engagement with large-scale renewable energy technologies: breaking the cycle of Nimbyism. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Climate Change, 2 (1), 19-26. http://www.cornwall.gov.uk/media/6012192/wind-turbine-operational.pdf http://www.cornwall.gov.uk/media/6011305/PV-sites-applications-larger-sites.pdf 29 Devine-Wright, P., 2011b. Enhancing place distinctiveness fosters public acceptance of tidal energy: a UK case study. Energy Policy, 39 (1), 83-93. Devine-Wright, P. 2012. Explaining “NIMBY” objections to a power line: the role of personal, place attachment and project-related factors. Environment and Behavior, 45 (6): 761-781. Dietz, S., and Stern, P., 2008. Public Participation in Environmental Assessment and Decision- Making. Washington: National Academies Press. Fuller, S., and McCauley, D., 2016. Framing energy justice: perspectives from activism and advocacy. Energy Research and Social Science, 11: 1–8. Goldthau, A., and Sovacool, B., 2012. The uniqueness of the energy security, justice, and governance problem. Energy Policy, 41, 232–240. Gross, C., 2007. Community perspectives of wind energy in Australia: the application of a justice and community fairness framework to increase social acceptance. Energy Policy, 35 (5), 2727–2736. Haggett, C., 2011. “Planning and persuasion”: public engagement in renewable energy decision-making. In P. Devine-Wright, ed. Renewable energy and the public, London: Earthscan, 15–28. Hall, S., 2013. Energy justice and ethical consumption: comparison, synthesis and lesson drawing. Local Environment: The International Journal of Justice and Sustainability, 18 (4), 422–437. Hansard, 2015. Communities and local government, local planning [online]. Available from: http://www.publications.parliament.uk/pa/cm201516/cmhansrd/cm150618/wmstext/1506 18m0001.htm [Accessed 2 September 2016]. Healy, N., and Barry, J., 2017. Politicizing energy justice and energy system transitions: fossil fuel divestment and a “just transition”. Energy Policy, 108, 451–459. Heffron, R., McCauley, D., and Sovacool, B., 2015. Resolving society's energy trilemma through the energy justice metric. Energy Policy, 87, 168–176. Hernández, D. 2015., Sacrifice along the energy continuum: a call for energy justice. Environmental Justice, 8, 151-156. http://www.publications.parliament.uk/pa/cm201516/cmhansrd/cm150618/wmstext/150618m0001.htm http://www.publications.parliament.uk/pa/cm201516/cmhansrd/cm150618/wmstext/150618m0001.htm 30 Honneth, A., 2004. Recognition and justice: outline of a plural theory of justice, Acta Sociologica, 47 (4), 351–364. Howard, T., 2015. Olive branches and idiot's guides: frameworks for community engagement in Australian wind farm development. Energy Policy, 78, 137–147. Jenkins, K., et al., 2014. Energy justice, a whole systems approach. Queen’s Political Review, II (2), 74–87. Jenkins, K., et al., 2016. Energy justice: A conceptual review. Energy Research and Social Science, 11, 174–182. Jenkins, K., McCauley, D., and Forman, A., 2017. Energy justice: a policy approach. Energy Policy, 105, 631–634. Jobert, A., Laborgne, P., and Mimler, S. 2007. Local acceptance of wind energy: factors of success identified in French and German case studies. Energy Policy, 35 (5), 2751–2760. Kechagia, M., 2017. National interests and local inconveniences: experiences of (in)justice in UK shale gas fracking. Paper presented at the Nordic Geographers Meeting, Stockholm, 21 June 2017 [online]. Available from https://stockholmuniversity.app.box.com/s/izcofytmtcdui5qgedxju21w7vl3axe7 [Accessed 28 June 2017]. Kelly-Reif, K., and Wing, S., 2016. Urban-rural exploitation: an underappreciated dimension of environmental injustice. Journal of Rural Studies, 47 (A), 350–358. Klinsky, S., and Dowlatabadi, H., 2009. Conceptualizations of justice in climate policy. Climate Policy, 9 (1), 88–108. Langer, K., et al., 2016. A qualitative analysis to understand the acceptance of wind energy in Bavaria. Renewable and Sustainable Energy Reviews, 64, 248–259. MacCoun, R., 2005. Voice, control and belonging: the double-edged sword of procedural fairness. Annual Review of Law and Social Science, 1, 171–201. Maguire, L., and Lind, E., 2003. Public participation in environmental decisions: stakeholders, authorities and procedural justice. International Journal of Global Environmental Issues, 3 (2), 133–148. https://stockholmuniversity.app.box.com/s/izcofytmtcdui5qgedxju21w7vl3axe7 31 Malin, S., and DeMaster, K., 2016. A devil's bargain: rural environmental injustices and hydraulic fracturing on Pennsylvania's farms. Journal of Rural Studies, 47 (A), 278-290. Mason, K., and Milbourne, P., 2014. Constructing a “landscape justice” for windfarm development: the case of Nant Y Moch, Wales. Geoforum, 53, 104–115. McCauley, D., et al., 2013. Advancing energy justice: the triumvirate of tenets. International Energy Law Review, 32 (3), 107–110. McClymont, K. and O'Hare, P. 2008. “We're not NIMBYs!” Contrasting local protest groups with idealised conceptions of sustainable communities. Local Environment, 13 (4): 321–335. Mckee, K., 2009. Post-Foucauldian governmentality: what does it offer critical social policy analysis? Critical Social Policy, 29 (3), 465–486. Mitchell, C., 2008. The political economy of sustainable energy. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. Murdoch, J., 2004. Putting discourse in its place: planning, sustainability and the urban capacity study. Area, 36 (1), 50–58. Ofgem., 2016. About the FiT scheme [online]. Available from: https://www.ofgem.gov.uk/environmental-programmes/fit/about-fit-scheme [Accessed 2 September 2016]. Ottinger, G., Hargrave, T., and Hopson, E., 2014. Procedural justice in wind facility siting: recommendations for state-led siting processes. Energy Policy, 65, 662–669. RenewableUK, 2015. Why renewables matter [online]. Available from: http://c.ymcdn.com/sites/www.renewableuk.com/resource/resmgr/publications/reports/w hy_renewables_matter.pdf [Accessed 2 September 2016]. Rose-Redwood, R., 2006. Governmentality, geography, and the geo-coded world. Progress in Human Geography, 30 (4), 469–486. Rowe, G. and Frewer, L., 2004. Evaluating public-participation exercises: a research agenda. Science, Technology, & Human Values, 29 (4), 512-556. Schlosberg, D., 2004. Reconceiving environmental justice: global movements and political theories. Environmental Politics, 13 (3), 517–540. https://www.ofgem.gov.uk/environmental-programmes/fit/about-fit-scheme http://c.ymcdn.com/sites/www.renewableuk.com/resource/resmgr/publications/reports/why_renewables_matter.pdf http://c.ymcdn.com/sites/www.renewableuk.com/resource/resmgr/publications/reports/why_renewables_matter.pdf 32 Schlosberg, D., 2007. Defining environmental justice: theories, movements and nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Simcock, N. 2016. Procedural justice and the implementation of community wind energy projects: a case study from South Yorkshire, UK. Land Use Policy, 59, 467-477. Skitka, L., Winquist, J., and Hutchinson, S., 2003. Are outcome fairness and outcome favourability distinguishable psychological constructs? A meta-analytic review. Social Justice Research, 16 (4), 309–341. Sovacool, B., 2014. What are we doing here? Analysing 15 years of energy scholarship and proposing a social science research agenda. Energy Research and Social Science, 1, 1–29. Sovacool, B., et al., 2016. Energy decisions reframed as justice and ethical concerns. Nature Energy, 1, 16024. Sovacool, B., Sidortsov, R., and Jones, B., 2013. Energy security, equality and justice. London: Routledge. Sovacool, B. and Dworkin, M., 2014. Global energy justice: principles, problems, and practices. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Swyngedouw, E., 2010. Apocalypse forever? Post-political populism and the spectre of climate change. Theory, Culture and Society, 27 (2–3), 213–232. Tingey, M., Webb, J., and Hawkey, D., 2017. Local authority engagement in UK energy systems: highlights from early findings. London: UKERC and Loughborough. Usher, S., 2013. Defending and transcending local identity through environmental discourse. Environmental Politics, 22 (5), 811-831. Walker, G., 2009. Beyond distribution and proximity: exploring the multiple spatialities of environmental justice. Antipode, 41 (4), 614–636. Walker, G., and Bulkeley, H., 2006. Geographies of environmental justice. Geoforum, 37 (5), 655–659. Walker, G., and Day. R., 2012. Fuel poverty as injustice: Integrating distribution, recognition and procedure in the struggle for affordable warmth. Energy Policy, 49, 69–75. 33 West, J., Bailey, I., and Winter, M., 2010. Renewable energy policy and public perceptions of renewable energy: a cultural theory approach. Energy Policy, 38 (10), 5739–5748. While, A., Jonas, A., and Gibbs, D., 2010. From sustainable development to carbon control: eco-state restructuring and the politics of urban and regional development. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers, 35 (1), 76–93. Wolsink, M., 2007. Wind power implementation: the nature of public attitudes: equity and fairness instead of “backyard motives”. Renewable and Sustainable Energy Reviews, 11 (6), 1188–1207. Young, I.M., 2000. Inclusion and democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Zoellner, J., Scheizer-Ries, P. and Wemheuer, C. 2008. Public acceptance of renewable energies: results from case studies. Energy Policy, 36 (11), 4136-4141. work_d2cihzgtobc2lgtmi646y3lp5q ---- 1 Von Hayek and Ordoliberalism on Justice Manuel Wörsdörfer 1 Abstract: Variations and disparities between von Hayek and Ordoliberalism can be detected on diverse levels: 1. philosophy of science, 2. setting dissimilar priorities, 3. social philosophy, 4. genesis of norms and 5. notion of freedom. As a consequence it is possible to make an important distinction within neoliberalism itself which contains at least two factions: von Hayek‟s evolutionary liberalism and German Ordoliberalism. The following essay not only takes the neoliberal separation of different varieties as granted; it proceeds further: it focuses on the topic of justice and elaborates the (slightly) differing conceptions of justice within neoliberalism. Thus, the specific contribution of the paper is that it adds a further, a sixth dimension of differences (which is highly interconnected with the already mentioned differing conceptions of genesis of norms). To put it differently: In the current paper I try to emphasize the (often neglected) subtle differences between von Hayek, Eucken, Röpke and Rüstow with special emphasis on their theories of justice. In this regard, I will not only focus on Eucken and von Hayek; instead, I will include the concepts of justice developed by Rüstow and Röpke as well and in consequence, broaden the perspective incorporating Eucken as a member of the Freiburg School of Law and Economics and Rüstow and Röpke as representatives of Ordoliberalism in the wider sense. The paper tackles these topics in three steps: After having briefly re-examined and discussed the existing literature and provided the reader with a literature overview on the decade-long debate on von Hayek and Ordoliberalism in the introductory chapter, part two describes von Hayek‟s conception of commutative justice respectively justice of rules and procedures (rather than end-state justice). The third part examines Eucken‟s, Rüstow‟s and Röpke‟s theory of justice which consists of a mixture of commutative and distributive justice. In the fourth paragraph I draw a comparison between the ideas of justice developed by Eucken, Röpke, Rüstow and von Hayek. The essay ends with a summary of my main findings. Keywords: Neoliberalism, Ordoliberalism, commutative and distributive justice, Walter Eucken, Friedrich August von Hayek. JEL Classification: B2, B3, B25, B52, P0 and Z1 1. Introductory Remarks: State of Research Many scholars and scientists have dealt with Ordoliberalism and von Hayek at great length and compared in particular the socio-economic theories of Walter Eucken and Friedrich August von Hayek. 2 To name just a few: Watrin (2000) analyzes the varying concepts of the state and government tasks. According to him, Eucken as a member of the Freiburg School of Law and Economics is favoring – more or less – a deliberately designed and „made‟ (constructivist) order while von Hayek on the other hand is highly in favor of an evolutionary, „grown‟ (spontaneous) order (i.e. constructivist rationalism vs. evolutionary/critical rationalism; see Hayek 1973). Streit and Wohlgemuth (2000a and 2000b) in turn point at the diverging leitmotivs underlying the conceptions of von Hayek and Eucken: In the centre of 1 Address for correspondence: Manuel Wörsdörfer, PhD candidate and research assistant of the Cluster of Excellence „The Formation of Normative Orders‟, Frankfurt University, Grueneburgplatz, 1, FB2, H.P.O. Box 47, 60323 Frankfurt am Main, Germany; e-mail: woersdoerfer@wiwi.uni-frankfurt.de. 2 The biographical and personal relationship-level (between von Hayek and Eucken) is presented in Karabelas 2010: pp. 69. mailto:woersdoerfer@wiwi.uni-frankfurt.de 2 Ordoliberalism is the topic of private power or – to put it differently – the question of how to avoid, eliminate or at least reduce the concentration of power in the economic and political sphere. To the contrary, von Hayek is not so much concerned with the problem of power as with the epistemological topic of knowledge. To be more precise: His major concern is the division or fragmentation of widely dispersed knowledge which can be utilized via competitive market processes operating as a discovery procedure. A similar approach as in Streit and Wohlgemuth (2000a and 2000b) and Watrin (2000) is presented by Kolev (2008). Kolev not only discusses the distinct roles of the state; additionally, he analyses Eucken‟s and von Hayek‟s concepts of monetary, competition and social policy as well. According to Pies (2001: pp. 123), the differences between Eucken and von Hayek are in fact merely of minor importance. The only true difference is that Eucken presents a theory of power while von Hayek presents a theory of knowledge. Finally, Bönker and Wagener (2001) are again emphasizing the differences between a self-generating, spontaneous formation of order and a political artifact-order. Besides the role of the state and the agenda of economic policy, they are referring to philosophy of science-aspects resulting from the diverging underlying leitmotivs already mentioned in the two essays by Streit and Wohlgemuth. In retrospect, it is striking that most of the just mentioned subsequent interpretations are highlighting the parallels while the differences are either of minor importance, as in the work of Pies, or they are presented one-sidedly: Von Hayek is often regarded as an Ordoliberal and the Freiburg School of Law and Economics, Ordoliberalism in the wider sense, and von Hayek are often talked about in the same breath (cp. Kolev 2010). The major differences are traced back to the diverging leitmotivs (power vs. knowledge) and/or the two concepts of order: made or grown order or in the Hayekian terminology: taxis and kosmos. These disparities are, no doubt, of eminent significance and they must not be underestimated and neglected. However, and that is essential to note, considerable differences can be found on different topics and not only on the just mentioned ones. Variations and disparities between von Hayek and Ordoliberalism in the wider sense can in fact be detected on diverse levels 3 : 1. philosophy of science: von Hayek‟s recognition of incomplete information, limits of reason and bounded rationality and his warning against pretence of knowledge vs. the ordoliberal quest for absolute truth and inherent epistemic optimism and malleability due to pure human reason; 2. setting dissimilar priorities: von Hayek‟s focus on the problem of knowledge and his re-interpretation of competition as a 3 The first two dimensions are mainly based on the literature mentioned prior. The third, fourth and fifth dimensions can be found in the work of Wörsdörfer 2010; 2011 and forthcoming. 3 discovery procedure vs. the ordoliberal focus on the problem of power and its re- interpretation of competition as an instrument of disempowerment; 4 3. social philosophy: von Hayek‟s focus on regulatory ethics vs. the ordoliberal combination of regulatory and individual/virtue ethics pegged to the topics of Gesellschaftskrisis and Vital Policy as one major peculiarity of German Ordoliberalism; 4. genesis of norms: von Hayek‟s cultural- evolutionary vs. the ordoliberal constructivist-elitist approach; and 5. notion of freedom: von Hayek‟s negative concept of liberty vs. the ordoliberal combination of negative and positive (Kantian) liberty. As a consequence it should be possible to make an important distinction within neoliberalism itself which contains at least two factions: von Hayek‟s evolutionary liberalism and German Ordoliberalism. 5 The current paper builds on the work of Renner (1999/2000), Quaas (2000), Hennecke (2008) and others evaluating the different varieties inside neoliberalism. Coming back once again to the literature review on the current state of research, what becomes clear and obvious is the fact that the theories of justice are more or less neglected. Only a few paragraphs are dedicated to this topic (cp. Bönker/Wagener 2001: pp. 190-191; Streit/Wohlgemuth 2000a: pp. 486-489 and Streit/Wohlgemuth 2000b: pp. 249-251). The only exception in this regard is Kolev. The following essay not only takes the neoliberal separation of different varieties stated by Renner et al. as granted; it proceeds further: it focuses on the topic of justice and elaborates the (slightly) differing conceptions of justice within neoliberalism. Thus, the specific contribution of the paper is that it fills the gap and that it adds a further, a sixth dimension of differences (which is highly interconnected with the already mentioned differing conceptions of genesis of norms). To put it differently: In the current paper I try to emphasize the (often neglected) subtle differences between von Hayek, Eucken, Röpke and Rüstow with special emphasis on their theories of justice. As stated above, I will not only focus on Eucken and von Hayek; instead, I will include the concepts of justice developed by Rüstow and Röpke as well and in consequence, broaden the perspective 4 In this regard von Hayek‟s (relatively) laissez faire attitude towards (private and natural) monopolies and large size corporations is remarkable (cp. Hayek 1979: pp. 77; Hennecke 2008: pp. 150). He even speaks of a „problem of antimonopoly legislation‟ due to the discretionary and arbitrary powers of public authorities intervening in market processes. His mistrust in state authorities is even higher than his mistrust in monopolies and big enterprises. “… it is not monopoly as such but only the prevention of competition which is harmful. […] a monopoly that rests entirely on superior performance is wholly praiseworthy …” (both: Hayek 1979: p. 83). 5 Furthermore, we have to distinguish between von Hayek, the Chicago School and Monetarism – all part of (modern) neoliberalism: On many occasions, von Hayek emphasizes the privatization of central banks, pleads for the „Denationalization of Money‟, a free market in money (i.e. free banking), and rejects the government monopoly on currency. In addition, he clearly criticizes (Friedman‟s) quantity theory of money (see e.g. Hennecke 2000; 2008: pp. 151 and Karabelas 2010: pp. 64). As a result, von Hayek is not a „Chicago Boy‟, although he was lecturing at the University of Chicago for more than a decade. Finally, von Hayek has to be (clearly) separated from Buchanan‟s Constitutional Economics, and Murray N. Rothbard and libertarian „anarcho-capitalism‟. 4 incorporating Eucken as a member of the Freiburg School of Law and Economics and Rüstow and Röpke as representatives of Ordoliberalism in the wider sense. The paper tackles these topics in three steps: After having briefly re-examined and discussed the existing literature and provided the reader with a literature overview on the decade-long debate on von Hayek and Ordoliberalism in the introductory chapter, part two describes von Hayek‟s conception of commutative justice respectively justice of rules and procedures (rather than end-state justice). The third part examines Eucken‟s, Rüstow‟s and Röpke‟s theory of justice which consists of a mixture of commutative and distributive justice. In the fourth paragraph I draw a comparison between the ideas of justice developed by Eucken, Röpke, Rüstow and von Hayek. The essay ends with a summary of my main findings. 2. Social Justice as a ‘Weasel-Word’? Von Hayek on Justice “It is now necessary clearly to distinguish between two wholly different problems which the demand for „social justice‟ raises in a market order. The first is whether within an economic order based on the market the concept of „social justice‟ has any meaning or content whatever. The second is whether it is possible to preserve a market order while imposing upon it (in the name of „social justice‟ or any other pretext) some pattern of remuneration based on the assessment of the performance or the needs of different individuals or groups by an authority possessing the power to enforce it. The answer to each of these questions is a clear no” (Hayek 1976: pp. 67). “… the addition of the adjective „social‟ makes them capable of meaning almost anything one likes. The word has indeed become one of the chief sources of confusion of political discourse and can probably no longer be reclaimed for a useful purpose” (Hayek 1976: pp. 79). Von Hayek denotes distributive or social justice as an “atavism” 6 (Hayek 1976/1996a), as an “illusion” (Hayek 1976/1996b; 1978/1996a: p. 63) and as a “weasel-word” (Hayek 1979/1996: p. 277) – mainly used by constructivists. 7 As a consequence, he pleads for a 6 According to von Hayek, social justice rests upon basic instincts, passions and traditions of small, face-to-face communities. Therefore, social justice regarded as a relic of pre-modern times prevents the transformation towards a modern, impersonal and abstract society of commerce. By relying on inherent instincts and primitive feelings, social justice concepts are exposed to misuse by prophets and constructivists (Hayek 1978/1996a: p. 55). 7 A similar critique is also forwarded against the ordoliberal „Third Way‟ and the concept of the Social Market Economy, often denounced as a blank or magic formula (Leer- or Zauberformel). In volume 2 of Law, Legislation and Liberty, von Hayek even speaks of social/distributive justice as an empty and meaningless concept. It is said to be meaningful only within organizations and/or a centrally planned economy. Moreover, he describes it as the “new religion of our time” (Hayek 1976: p. xii), as a “quasi-religious superstition” (both: p. 66), as a “cult” (p. 99) and as a “pseudo-ethics” (Hayek 1979: p. 135). 5 „market economy without any attributes‟. According to von Hayek, social justice is often introduced as a way to legitimize special interests and exclusive privileges, and to grant permissions and exceptions (Hayek 1973/1996: pp. 252; 1976/1996a: pp. 181). Due to its vulnerability to the misuse of rent seeking groups, social justice is irreconcilable with a market economy in the terms of von Hayek (Hayek 1973/1996: p. 258): i.e. the market as a self-regulating, spontaneous order 8 (kosmos) (e.g. Hayek 1966/1996: 263) and as a product of cultural evolution (see Hayek 1973: pp. 8 and 1983/1996) relying on abstract, impersonal and negative general rules or prohibitions independent of particular purposes 9 and on the notion of negative freedom (Hayek 1978/1996b: p. 230; 1979: pp. 130). Von Hayek‟s reasons for dismissing the concept of social justice are manifold (Hayek 1976/1996b: pp. 197): First of all, social justice (and its constructivist organization) reduces productivity, economic efficiency and, therefore, the overall wealth of a society – by not drawing on competition as a discovery procedure (Hayek 1968/2002; 1979: pp. 67) and by not drawing on the decentralized individual knowledge and know-how (Hayek 1976/1996a: p. 191; 1978/1996a: p. 61). 10 Second, social justice and the accompanying (authoritative) process of correcting redistribution to the benefit of certain population groups (Hayek 1976/1996a: p. 189) is necessarily attached to coercion and state interventionism resulting in a threat to individual liberty (Hayek 1976/1996a: p. 191; 1976/1996b: pp. 194; 1978/1996b: p. 236 11 ). Third and finally, social justice cannot be realized due to the fact that a common criterion of justice is missing. There is simply no objective criterion of distributive justice and it seems unlikely that a common consent on what justice involves will be reached (Hayek 1976/1996a: p. 182; 1978/1996b: p. 236)). By unilaterally and authoritatively prescribing a definition of justice and the way to implement a program of social justice, the problem of pretence of knowledge (Hayek 1944/2007: pp. 100; 1974/1996) arises: It is not feasible for the planning authorities to take full account of the countless changing individual needs of consumers; no one can survey the socio-economic process as a whole. Concretely, nobody 8 Von Hayek distinguishes two kinds of „order‟: a spontaneous order and a constructivist organization (Hayek 1966/1996: pp. 263; 1970/1996; 1973: pp. 35). 9 General abstract rules – together with spontaneous order and the use of decentralized information via markets and competition – are distinctive of an open society (cp. Popper 1957/2003; 1958/2003; Hayek 1976/1996a). These kinds of rules prescribe what individuals are not to do; otherwise, they are free to pursue their own personal interests. 10 Only purpose-free and end-independent general rules – rather than rules based on discretionary power and outcome considerations – allow for economic freedom in the Hayekian sense and, as a consequence, foster the overall wealth of a nation; see also Hayek 1944/2007: p. 96: “… division of knowledge between individuals whose separate efforts are coordinated by the impersonal mechanism for transmitting the relevant information known by us as the price system.” 11 Cp. Hayek 1944/2007: p. 117: “… any policy aiming directly at a substantive ideal of distributive justice must lead to the destruction of the Rule of Law.” 6 knows how a just income distribution has to look like, and an externally imposed scale of incomes is necessarily connected with the violation of consumer sovereignty and will lead to totalitarian mastery (Hayek 1976/1996b: pp. 197). Von Hayek even claims that distributive justice leads to economic dictatorship (Hayek 1976/1996b: p. 198). However, von Hayek is not dismissing the concept of justice as a whole; rather, although he is highly critical of the concept of (re-)distributive or social justice, he defends the concept of commutative justice respectively justice of rules, procedures and institutions (Hayek 1944/2007: p. 113). Even though it is not appropriate to meaningfully assess the results of the market process according to values of social or distributive justice (i.e. market outcomes are from an ethical perspective morally neutral and the market process itself is anonymous and ethically indifferent), it is indeed permissible to evaluate the market behavior of each of the market transaction partners. Therefore, the market game – von Hayek often refers to the market game as catallaxy (i.e. exchange game) – is liable to (procedural) justice requirements. In this regard, Vanberg (2006) distinguishes three levels of potential justice considerations: 1. rules of the game (i.e. justice of order of rules/constitution of the market) 12 ; 2. plays of the game (i.e. justice of behavior respectively codes of conduct of market players); 3. results of the game (i.e. justice of outcomes of market mechanisms). As stated by von Hayek and Vanberg, the rules of the game have to be mainly negative, abstract and universally applicable. Their task is to legally frame and regulate the market as an arena of voluntary exchange and cooperation for mutual benefits. Formal rules and institutions have to be based on consensual constitutional interests and they have to be mutually and voluntarily agreeable. Under the condition that the rules of the game are fair and overall acceptable and that the behavior of each participant complies with the rules of the game, the results of the game have to be taken as they are (i.e. there is no such thing as a redistribution according to social justice criteria). 13 The outcomes of an ex-ante specified course of the game have to be accepted with 12 Von Hayek points out that a just behavioural code is vital for a peaceful society of free individuals; however, the attempt to realise social justice is mutually incompatible with such a society (Hayek 1976/1996a: p. 181). 13 Cp. Hayek 1978/1996b: p. 237: „Der Liberalismus verlangt nur, daß die Bedingungen oder die Spielregeln, durch welche die relativen Positionen der verschiedenen Menschen bestimmt werden, gerecht sind […], jedoch nicht, daß die Ergebnisse des Prozesses im einzelnen für die verschiedenen Menschen gerecht sind …“ Essential are formal equality, impartiality, fairness, the absence of discriminations of any kind, and equality of opportunity. Even an income redistribution via a progressive fiscal system is not allowed due to the fact that it violates the principle of equal treatment, non-arbitrariness and equality before the law (i.e. taxation has to be conducted according to the principle of equality and not for the purpose of redistribution; cp. Hayek 1973/1996: p. 256; 1978/1996b: p. 238). Furthermore, redistribution is tied to the emergence of the modern welfare state with its large machinery of bureaucracy and the increase of state control even in the economic sector, while at the same time personal liberty is threatened (cp. Hayek 1960). What is needed is a demarcation of the state‟s tasks and a clear, transparent and strict definition of the limits of responsibility and powers of p ublic authorities. In sum, the reallocation of incomes via a progressive tax system and to the benefit of the worst-off in a society is 7 all their inequalities and randomness; i.e. the results of market mechanism evade entirely their evaluation according to justice criteria or in other words: it is not permissible to apply moral categories on the outcomes of market processes, von Hayek (1973/1996: pp. 258; 1976/1996b: p. 200) states. It is merely possible to agree on procedural justice; yet, there is no guarantee of overall advantages and gains once the rules of the game have been implemented. Each game involves several risks and potential losses which have to be taken into account (ex-post correction or redistribution is not permissible once an agreement of rules and procedures has been reached). What is important is that the results of the game are coming into being under fair and just conditions and that each individual pursues his or her self- interests within the legally defined framework (i.e. rule-based adherence and compliance with the legislation). In sum: justice of procedures and rules (i.e. universal applicability of consensual rules independent of special interests) – yes; justice of (equal/egalitarian 14 ) results and outcomes including just wages, just prices and a just income distribution 15 – no! Von Hayek clearly favors the concept of commutative justice and he abhors distributive or social justice focusing solely on outcomes and reallocation (see Hayek 1978/1996b: pp. 235). 16 Fundamental to von Hayek‟s concept of commutative justice are the already mentioned abstract general rules, the freedom to enter into contracts respectively contract law, private property and a socio-economic and legal framework or an (impersonal) order of rules guaranteeing the universal applicability and the equal compliance to rules (i.e. fairness of the game) and the prevention of fraud and deception. 17 In addition, they should guarantee the equal and impartial treatment and non-discrimination of persons. By doing so, commutative justice is able to increase the overall wealth of a society and, thus, the general well-being of an average individual – even the poor are much better-off in a market society fulfilling the criteria of von Hayek compared to a centrally administered economy. According to von at odds with (von Hayek‟s) principle of equality before the law (cp. Hayek 1978/1996b: p. 238; see also Hayek 1960: pp. 306). 14 Von Hayek is highly critical of socio-economic egalitarianism and uniformist minimum wages: cp. Hayek 1976/1996b: p. 202; 1960: pp. 48; pp. 85; pp. 285. From a Hayekian perspective, egalitarianism is highly correlated with discrimination and coercion. It is, therefore, incompatible with von Hayek‟s definition of liberty as the absence of constraint and compulsion. In Law, Legislation and Liberty, he clearly warns against egalitarianism and material equality (Hayek 1976: pp. 80) due to the fact that it requires economic interventionism for its fulfillment: absolute equality of material positions equals the submission of great masses under the command of some elite who manages the affairs of others. Therefore, egalitarianism can only be met by a government with despotic and totalitarian powers. 15 Cp. Hayek 1944/2007: p. 140: “… what is a “just price” or a “fair wage“?“ 16 „… sie beruht auf der Überzeugung, daß es möglich sei, objektive Regeln richtigen Verhaltens unabhängig von Sonderinteressen zu entdecken, und sie fragt nur, ob das menschliche Verhalten gerecht ist oder die Regeln, die es leiten, aber nicht, welche Ergebnisse dieses Verhalten für einzelne Menschen oder Gruppen zeitigt“ (Hayek 1978/1996b: p. 235). 17 State authorities are responsible for monitoring the adherence to the rules of the game and for taking care, that individual behaviour pursuing self-interests within the rules of the game leads to commonly desirable results. 8 Hayek, commutative justice has no regard for personal needs and individual merits (in the sense of Verdienst and Bedürfnis) (Hayek 1976/1996a: p. 186; 1976/1996b: p. 196; 1960: pp. 231). 18 What is important is the (economic) value of a performance in the eye of a recipient (Hayek 1976/1996b: p. 196). 19 Each payment correlates to the worth of a performance – pointing again at the importance of the principle of equivalence. Although it is not advisable from a Hayekian perspective to correct the (distributive) outcomes of market processes or to intervene in the market mechanism itself as (process-political) distributive justice would do, there remains one way open for social reforms: changing or correcting the rules of the game or reforming the Ordnungspolitik-level as Eucken claims. 20 2.1. Law, Legislation and Liberty: The Mirage of Social Justice Since Hayek‟s trilogy Law Legislation and Liberty is often considered as his opus magnum – especially in the field of the theory of justice – it is essential to incorporate a paragraph here before analyzing in detail the ordoliberal concept of justice. Here, what becomes clear is the interconnectedness of his theory of impersonal justice based on formal (abstract and end- independent) rules with the twin-concepts of cultural evolution and spontaneous order. At the centre of von Hayek‟s negative theory of justice (Hayek 1979: pp. 130) are the legal rules of just conduct and the design of political institutions (Hayek 1976: p. 100). It is not a positive conception of justice which makes it an obligation of administration and government to distribute and reallocate wealth equally among citizens (p. 103). Rather, what is important is to evade injustice and, thus, approach the (unattainable) ideal state of absence of injustice (p. 54). As claimed by von Hayek, a positive (i.e. agreeable and consensual) criterion of justice does simply not exist (p. 42), 21 only negative ones are obtainable indicating what is unjust. Merely an objective and that means an interpersonally valid (negative) test of injustice 18 See also Hayek 1976: p. 82: “Since people will differ in many attributes which government cannot alter, to secure for them the same material position would require that government treat them very differently. […] to compensate for those disadvantages and deficiencies it could not directly alter.” He continues to say: “… because these rewards correspond not to the value which their services have for their fellows, but to the moral merit or desert the persons are deemed to have earned, they lose the guiding function they have in the market order and would have to be replaced by the commands of the directing authority”. 19 Von Hayek (1976: p. 72) notes: “… these values which their services will have to their fellows will often have not relations to their individual merits or needs.” 20 “… although we can endeavour to improve a spontaneous order by revising the general rules on which it rests, and can supplement its results by the efforts of various organizations, we cannot improve the results by specific commands that deprive its members of the possibility of using their knowledge for their purposes” (Hayek 1973: p. 51). 21 I.e. complete lack of a recognized standard of „social justice (cp. Hayek 1976: pp. 90): “… there are no practicable standards of merit, deserts, or needs, on which in a market order the distribution of material benefits could be based …” (here: p. 91). 9 enables us gradually to remove these kinds of rules which prove to be unjust and which are, therefore, not universalizable. 22 Instead of granting (non-achievable and non-enforceable) positive rights, the socio-political order should rest on negative rights and commutative justice. Such an ideal of impersonal justice (rather than sectional justice) is based on formal rules, and to be more precise, it is based on spontaneously grown rules, not on deliberately planned/made rules brought about by deliberate human design (i.e. “the result of human action but not of human design” (Hayek (following Ferguson) 1973: p. 20)). This evolutionary approach to law involves the rejection of the interpretation of law as a deliberate construct of super-natural forces (Hayek 1976: p. 60). According to von Hayek, it is not possible in a Great Society to agree on ends. Agreement can only be reached on means or to put it differently on rules of just conduct 23 : “… rules of just conduct serve not (concrete or particular) ends but (abstract and generic) values …” (p. 14). These rules intend to apply for an indefinite period, “… to an unknown number of future instances and to the acts of an unknown number of persons, and merely states certain attributes which any such action ought to possess …” (p. 14; see also p. 35 and 130). These abstract rules embody the knowledge and traditional experience which has been generated and transmitted over time. Thus, they are a device, a tool for coping with human ignorance and uncertainty. Abstract rules are the guides in a world in which most things are unknown (i.e. limits of reason and lack of knowledge 24 ; see pp. 8). The big advantage of such rules – together with other impersonal and abstract mechanisms like competitive markets – is the utilization of factual knowledge widely dispersed among thousands of individuals (i.e. fragmentation of knowledge (Hayek 1973: p. 14; 1976: p. 8)). The task of public authorities is the enforcement of the observance of abstract rules of (just) conduct, the preservation of a rule-governed spontaneous order (kosmos instead of taxis/organization with its end-governed character): “Only if applied universally, without regard to particular effects, will they serve the permanent preservation of the abstract order, a timeless purpose which will continue to assist the individuals in the pursuit of their contemporary and still unknown aims. Those rules 22 See Hayek 1976: p. 43: “… „juridical laws [must] abstract altogether from our ends, they are essentially negative and limiting principles which merely restrict our exercise of freedom.‟” 23 “… individuals are not required to agree on ends but only on means which are capable of serving a great variety of purposes and which each hopes will assist him in the pursuit of his own purposes” (Hayek 1976: p. 3). 24 Cp. Hayek 1976: p. 39: “It is as much because we lack the knowledge of a common hierarchy of the importance of the particular ends of different individuals as because we lack the knowledge of particular facts, that the order of the Great Society must be brought about by the observance of abstract and end-independent rules.” Due to the inherent limits of knowledge and reason it is simply not possible to rationally construct the whole of society, von Hayek continues to say: “But an order of the complexity of modern society can be designed neither as a whole, nor by shaping each part separately without regard to the rest, but only by consistently adhering to certain principles throughout a process of evolution” (Hayek 1973: p. 60). 10 which are common values serve the maintenance of an order of whose existence those who apply them are often not even aware” (p. 17). The key feature of such negative rules restraining individual action is their generalization and universal applicability 25 (cp. Kant‟s test of unversalizability, the Categorical Imperative: i.e. principle of treating all under the same rules). Moreover, they are end-independent and purpose-free, that means that they serve unknown particular ends. Therefore, they are mainly responsible – together with the constitutional state – for forming and preserving a spontaneous order or in Böhm‟s terminology: a private law society. “What rules of just conduct in fact do is to say under what conditions this or that action will be within the range of the permissible; but they leave it to the individuals under these rules to create their own protected domain. […] Since the consequences of applying rules of just conduct will always depend on factual circumstances which are not determined by these rules, we cannot measure the justice of the application of a rule by the result it will produce in a particular case” (pp. 37). Negative rules of just conduct are primarily prohibitions of unjust behavior; in addition: it is only feasible to judge actions by rules, not by particular results. Particular results of a socio-economic process – which follow from the application of rules to an individual case – cannot be regarded as just or unjust (p. 32). So, negative rules do not impose any duties or obligations on anyone. Von Hayek notes: “Justice is not concerned with those unintended consequences of a spontaneous order which have not been deliberately brought about by anybody. The rules of just conduct thus merely serve to prevent conflict and to facilitate co-operation by eliminating some sources of uncertainty” (p. 38). Von Hayek‟s problem with social justice is that it rolls back the transition from a small-face- to-face-society towards an abstract and spontaneous order of the Great Society. It will inevitably lead into a path towards an end-connected tribal society (teleocracy) and gradually destroy the rule-connected open society (nomocracy) (p. 38). In this regard von Hayek speaks of distributive justice as an atavism and as Rousseauian nostalgia: “They are an atavism, a vain attempt to impose upon the Open Society the morals of the tribal society which, if it prevails, must not only destroy the Great Society …” (p. 147). He continues to say: “Our present moral views undoubtedly still contain layers or strata deriving from earlier phases of the evolution of human societies – the small horde to the organized tribe, the still larger groups of clans and the other successive steps towards the Great Society” (p. 42). The (alleged) revival of „tribal ethics‟ with its persistent conflict between tribal morals and 25 According to von Hayek (1976: p. 143) “universal justice [has to be] equally applicable to the stranger and to the member of the group.” 11 commutative justice of the Great Society, with its clash between the sense of loyalty and the sense of negative justice (p. 147), and with its all-pervading loyalty to particular groups and communities is the greatest obstacle to a universal application of rules of just conduct. Such a revival of ancestral sentiments and organizational thinking is according to von Hayek highly related to the ideologies of socialism and nationalism. They are the main driving forces behind the prevalent constructivist rationalism and the decline in the understanding of the operation of markets (p. 134). Social justice with its anthropomorphism and personification of justice and society (Hayek 1973: pp. 26; 1976: p. 75) “serves [at least from a Hayekian perspective] to support deep-seated emotions that are threatening to destroy the Great Society” (p. 133; i.e. threat of the totalitarian state). 26 As said by von Hayek, a gradual transformation from commutative to distributive justice is currently taking place. This self-accelerating 27 process threatens most values of a free society, since distributive justice is wholly incompatible with the rule of law and with freedom under the law. In the end, it will directly lead to socialism and despotism subordinating citizens to authority and placing the duty of justice on authorities with power to command and coerce people (i.e. totalitarian trend). In the words of von Hayek: Social justice serves as “the Trojan Horse through which totalitarianism has entered” (p. 136). The appeal to social justice and the demand of a just distribution of wealth leads to government action and intervention on behalf of special interest groups (p. 65). These particular rent seeking groups “… have learnt to employ the open sesame of „social justice‟” (p. 67) and succeeded in “clothing their demands with the aura of legitimacy […] by representing them as a requirement of „social justice‟” (p. 141). In consequence, the call to society/public authorities in the name of social justice and the misusage of the term distributive justice has opened the floodgates “to the demand by all who found their relative position threatened that their position be protected by government action” (p. 140). Moreover, it promotes the belief that long established positions create a just expectation that they will persist and it reinforces the idea that we morally deserve what we have earned in earlier periods (pp. 93): hence, social justice leads to the protection of habitual and familiarized positions and entrenched vested interests – often camouflaged as an appeal to social justice and often disregarding the common interest of society (see e.g. p. 96). In addition, it leads to a 26 Cp. Hayek 1976: p. 136: “The values which still survive from the small end-connected groups whose coherence depended upon them, are, however, not only different from, but often incompatible with, the values which make possible the peaceful coexistence of large numbers in the Open Society. The belief that while we pursue the new ideal of this Great Society in which all human beings are regarded as equal, we can also preserve the different ideals of the small closed society, is an illusion.” 27 “So long as the belief in „social justice‟ governs political action, this process must progressively approach nearer and nearer to a totalitarian system” (i.e. road to serfdom; Hayek 1976: p. 68). 12 struggle of power of organized interests in which arguments of social justice serve merely as pretexts and pretences for claims for privileges. Thus, they will destruct the Great Society with its freedom of discrimination from within (i.e. fragility of the liberal open society). Coming back once again to the already discussed implications of market mechanisms it is plausible from a Hayekian perspective that the concept of justice is not applicable to the results of a spontaneous order: the outcomes of market processes are simply not unjust, because: “Those shares are the outcome of a process the effect of which on particular people was neither intended nor foreseen by anyone when the institutions first appeared …” (p. 64). “There is no need morally to justify specific distributions (of income or wealth) which have not been brought about deliberately but are the outcome of a game that is played because it improves the chances of all. In such a game nobody „treats‟ people differently and it is entirely consistent with respecting all people equally that the outcome of the game for different people is very different” (p. 117). In a free and pluralistic society which lacks a common hierarchy of ends, the market order does not serve a single order or hierarchy of ends; its activities are not directed by a unique scale of ends (pp. 107). The market order, or as von Hayek describes it, the game of catallaxy 28 is a wealth-creating and poverty-eliminating game. It is a challenging competition played by individuals according to rules and decided by superior skill, talent, strengths and fortune. Von Hayek notes: “A catallaxy is thus the special kind of spontaneous order produced by the market through people acting within the rules of the law of property, tort and contract” (p. 109). “Even in a game with equal chances for all players there will be some winners and some losers” (p. 126). “In such a game in which the results for the individuals depend partly on chance and partly on their skill, there is evidently no sense in calling the outcome either just or unjust” (p. 126). Justice is simply the wrong category of evaluating market processes. As stated by von Hayek, only the conduct of the players but not the results of the economic contest can be just or unjust (see p. 70). The market order is a game partly of skill and partly of chance with unpredictable outcomes (determined by skill and luck) and with winners and losers at the same time. What justice requires are the fairness of the game and the exclusion of cheating, fraud, oppression and monopoly powers. 29 “The remunerations which the individuals and groups receive in the market are thus determined by what these services are worth to those who receive them… [and they are totally unrelated with needs and merits]” (p. 76). “… all that counts is the 28 I.e. discovery procedure which the competitive market order constitutes: “It is by this conveying of information in coded form that the competitive efforts of the market game secure the utilization of widely dispersed knowledge” (Hayek 1973: p. 117). And von Hayek continues to say: “… price mechanism operates as a medium of communicating knowledge” (p. 125). 29 See Hayek 1976: pp.73: “it was only „the way in which competition was carried on, not its results‟…” 13 (marginal) value the services have to those to whom they are rendered. […] based on the values the services have to the user and not on an assessment of merit earned.” (p. 92). Von Hayek is convinced that all “… the attempts to „correct‟ the results of the market in the direction of „social justice‟ have probably produced more injustice in the form of new privileges, obstacles to mobility and frustration of efforts that they have contributed to the alleviation of the lot of the poor” (pp. 139). Thus, it is essential – at least from a Hayekian perspective – to abide by the market result also when it turns against us. 3. The Ordoliberal Synthesis of Commutative and Distributive Justice 3.1. Eucken’s Theory of Justice Contrary to von Hayek, Walter Eucken‟s concept of justice is multidimensional, incorporating commutative and distributive justice elements as well as justice of rules, procedures, and institutions elements. 30 Even though Eucken is aware of the inherent problems of distributive or social justice – namely the potential institutionalization of discretionary powers 31 via opening gateways for special interest groups leading into a Hayekian „Road to Serfdom‟ (i.e. slippery slope argument) – he is also conscious of the social question 32 as one major 30 See also Vogt 1999/2009; Klump/Wörsdörfer 2010 and chapter 7.3 (Introductory Remarks) in: Wörsdörfer 2011. 31 Two arguments speak against discretionary interventions and process policy and for preferring a rule- constrained and rule-oriented policy over an interventionist, outcome-focused economic policy: first of all, the cognitive limits of (human) knowledge mentioned by von Hayek (i.e. constructivist rationalism commits the following faults: pretence of knowledge, absent recognition of the limits of rational control, defiance of the complex interdependencies in socio-economic systems) and secondly, the fact that discretionary interventionist government policy is much more vulnerable to rent-seeking than a government constrained in its decisions by general rules (cp. the Freiburg School of Law and Economics). 32 Eucken distinguishes three different kinds of social questions through the ages: 1. stage of injustice and inequality of distribution (starting with the industrial revolution and lasting until World War I), 2. stage of (mass) long-term unemployment (1920ies/1930ies), and 3. stage of overcoming insecurity stemming from unemployment, but erosion of a new form of uncertainty, injustice and insufficient supply of necessary goods and services resulting from socio-economic and political power concentration (since the mid-1930ies; Eucken 2001: pp. 45). The status quo is now dominated by powerful organizations (i.e. cartels, trusts, employer‟s association and trade/labor unions) and the present economic policy assumes the shape of corporatism and equals a centrally planned economy. All this caused a tremendous shift of the environmental conditions of the working class which can be characterized by three distinct aspects: scant supply of goods and services, injustice of distribution and insecurity. So the present social question incorporates all the elements of the previous ones. Moreover, a new kind of people is – as a direct consequence of the new social question – in the making: mass people that are solely dependent on the state; their human freedom is endangered and they equal (spare) parts within the big societal machine („Ein neuer Menschentypus ist im Entstehen, der aus vermaßten, vom Staate abhängigen Menschen besteht. Das ganze Leben wird allmählich verstaatlicht“ (Eucken 1948: p. 331)). At the heart of the new social question is, therefore, personal freedom (i.e. social problem: subservience of the individual to a massive and bureaucratic state machine, in which the individual becomes a means for the achievements of the ends of the ruling class; cp. Sally 1996): Security and social justice cannot be achieved without individual liberty. Thus, freedom, justice and security are inseparable; they are intertwined and not opposed to each other (cp. Eucken 2001: pp. 38). Eucken notes: „Die Unfreiheit ermöglichte den Druck auf die Daseinsbedingungen. Die Herrschaft privater oder öffentlicher Machtkörper gefährdete die Durchsetzung der Gerechtigkeit; und mangelnde Sicherheit entsprang aus mangelnder Freiheit. Ohne Freiheit der Person ist die 14 consequence of the industrial revolution. Thus, Eucken and other Ordoliberals endeavor to overcome the (new) social question – which is interlinked with the problem of socio- economic power – by granting social security, a minimum subsistence level respectively basic social care and if needed guaranteed minimum wages – and so they are referring to re- distributive instruments as well (even though the focus remains on commutative justice). It is striking that Eucken does not provide the reader with a clear-cut and distinct definition of (social) justice. He does not offer a unified concept of justice and the normative-philosophical foundations remain fairly vague (a similar accusation is – by the way – applicable to Eucken‟s concept of liberty). Nonetheless, Eucken‟s understanding of justice is integrated in his dual criteria requirement which has to be fulfilled by an ordoliberal socio-economic order: such an order has to be functioning and humane at once (the latter is often used as a synonym for freedom and (social) justice). In general, Eucken‟s competitive order is a good way to reach (social) justice: the formation of incomes – based on the notion of private property as an eminent pre-condition of liberty and the freedom to enter into contracts – is subject to the control and sanctioning mechanisms of competition and liability (Eucken 1952/2004: p. 275; pp. 279; p. 317). Moreover, the competitive order with its focus on Ordnungspolitik is responsible for dissolving market powers, for controlling monopolies, cartels, trusts and syndicates, and for preventing the abuse of discretionary powers mainly used by rent seekers (cp. Eucken‟s constituent and regulative principles in: Eucken 1952/2004: pp. 254). Consequently, an approximately power- free socio-economic order guarantees a relatively just income distribution by taking scarcities and shortages into consideration but not market powers 33 (Eucken 1952/2004: p. 316). To put it differently: Market processes which stick to ordoliberal principles are in general fair and just. Such an order does not only promote the overall wealth of a society (cp. the above chapter on von Hayek); it also adheres to the principle of performance and capability (Leistungsfähigkeitsprinzip) and what is most important, it is in accordance with justice of soziale Frage nicht zu lösen“ (Eucken 2001: p. 45). The best way to solve or to overcome the social question is not the adopted path or road to welfare state – this kind of social policy has often lead to an aggravation of the social question; instead, what is necessary is the creation of an ordoliberal competitive order with its unique unity of social- and constitutional ordering policy (i.e. Einheit von Sozial- und Wirtschaftsverfassungspolitik). Social justice may be achieved (and the social question may be overcome) via market-conforming interventions of social policy together with the establishment of a functioning institutional framework ensuring and protecting civil rights and liberties and a humane and dignified life by removing (excessive) private and public power concentrations. Social policy in the sense of being part of ordering policy is socially legitimate when it guarantees individual freedom and when it acts as an instrument of disempowerment. The (solving of the) social question is therefore highly related with the question of personal freedom and the negation of socio-economic power (see also Eucken 1952/2004: pp. 122 and pp. 185; Becker 1965; Külp 2000). 33 On the contrary, positions based on market powers are distorting the just generation of incomes and leading to an unjust distribution of incomes. 15 contracts and exchange (Vertrags- and Tauschgerechtigkeit). The freedom to enter into contracts – another important constituent principle established by Eucken – ensures the compliance of voluntarily closed transactions and businesses; commutative justice, thus, enables the just exchange of economic competencies (Eucken 1952/2004: pp. 315). Hence, justice is in a certain way equivalent to the outcomes of market processes – provided that power structures (and especially the abuse of powers) are mainly absent, competition on the merits and in terms of better services to consumers (Leistungswettbewerb) is implemented within the ordoliberal framework and guaranteed by the state authorities, and market transactions are carried out voluntarily by equal transaction partners (i.e. buyers and sellers alike) in a state of private autonomy (cp. Böhm‟s concept of a private law society (1966/1980)). On those conditions – referring to the ordoliberal topic of power –, economic cooperation and the division of labor ensures a level of efficiency and productivity which enhances the public good. From an ordoliberal (and Hayekian) perspective, the market is regarded as a democratic judge; market processes incorporate in a certain way democratic elements (cp. Röpke Civitas Humana: p. 61; 1942: pp. 142; 1950: p. 205ff.; Böhm 1966/1980: pp. 119; Eucken 1950/1996: p. 340). Market results are seen as a democratic plebiscite (depending on consumer‟s free choices) – given that it is a voluntary and reciprocal organization of exchanges with mutual benefits and that it takes place within a socio-economic order of complete competition (vollständiger Wettbewerb) and a minimized level of power and dependencies. Provided that all these requirements are met, the Ordoliberals speak of a market democracy in which the consumer is the sovereign and the director of the economic process and in which the producers have to follow and answer the consumer‟s wishes and preferences (i.e. consumarchy; cp. Röpke 1942: pp. 142; 1950: pp. 205). That is the ideal portrayal of the competitive order envisioned by Ordoliberalism (in the long run). So far, similarities in the Hayekian and the ordoliberal concepts of justice exist. But, many Ordoliberals go one step further in the direction of social justice; they accredit the inevitability of distributive justice elements and as a result, they deviate from the Hayekian notion of commutative justice. The Ordoliberals are not unworldly, quixotic or utopian, and they are fully aware of the existing problems. Eucken and others are not oblivious to possible socio-ethical deficiencies which can occur within the ordoliberal competitive order (Eucken 1952/2004: pp. 291). Thus, it is likely that deficiencies with regard to income distribution generated by market mechanisms can occur (Eucken 1952/2004: p. 318). In this instance, a (market-conforming) 16 correction is needed in order to prevent social cases of hardship (Eucken 1952/2004: pp. 300 and p. 318). Accordingly, Eucken develops certain regulating principles, e.g. the correction of negative external effects 34 , social policy (Eucken 1953: p. 24) and income policy, particularly progressive taxation according to the ability to pay principle 35 as one instrument for state- controlled redistribution (Dietze/Eucken/Lampe 1941/1942: p. 89). The aim is to secure a minimum standard of living – in special cases minimum wages are appropriate (Eucken 1952/2004: pp. 303) and in general, exploitative wages are prohibited (Dietze/Eucken/Lampe 1943/2008: p. 110). Additionally, Eucken strives to implement a humane labor market which is characterized by a far-reaching balance between employees and employers and an elimination of re-feudalization. Notably, Eucken admits that labor is not a commodity (Eucken 1952/2004: p. 322)! Eucken writes: “What matters is that the labor market is organized in a humane fashion. In this regard, the following aspects have to be considered: the workman does not sell himself as a person, he does sell his services. In order to avoid exploitation, re-feudalization (Vermachtung) has to be counteracted. The relationship between [labor market] partners should be balanced. Provision for security and retributive justice is not left to the goodwill of individuals or left to chance, in a manner of speaking; rather it is subject to Ordnungspolitik” (Eucken 1952/2004: p. 322; translated by the author). Hecker (2008: pp. 213) observes correctly that Eucken integrates basic elements of social justice into his principles of economic policy and that a fundamental openness exists within Eucken‟s competitive order in terms of market-conform socio-political corrections and redistributions – naturally within certain boundaries (cp. Eucken 1952/2004: p. 301). 36 34 The correction of negative external effects can also be seen as a part of inter-generational justice due to the fact that it incorporates environmental protection and that it strives for a sustainable economic development. The correction of external effects is discussed in ecological terms and highly related to a lasting ecological policy (see Eucken 1952/2004: pp. 301; cp. also Müller-Armack, name-giver and one of the most prominent representatives of German social market economy, 1959/1976: p. 265; 1960/1981: pp. 71; Erhard/Müller- Armack 1972: pp. 298). 35 Cp. on the contrary Hayek 1960: pp. 306, where von Hayek pleads for a proportionate instead of a progressive taxation system. 36 Cp. also Nutzinger/Hecker 2008: pp. 557: „… prinzipiell anerkannten Aspekt der sozialen Gerechtigkeit […], dass ethische Aspekte jenseits der Tauschgerechtigkeit […] in Form einer angemessenen Rahmenordnung zwar berücksichtigt, aber gerade dadurch aus dem ökonomischen Prozess ausgelagert wurden. […] Gerechtigkeit jenseits der iustitia commutativa wird nicht mehr in den einzelnen Tauschakten, sondern in den Rahmenbedingungen des Wirtschaftens verortet“ (p. 557). „Bei der Diskussion der konstituierenden Prinzipien betont Eucken sehr dezidiert seine Überzeugung, dass ungleiche Vermögens- und Einkommensverteilungen […] im Wesentlichen als Folge unzureichenden Wettbewerbs anzusehen sind, sodass die von ihm angestrebte wirtschaftspolitische Sicherung der Wettbewerbsordnung einen Großteil der Problematik von selbst lösen würde. Eucken erkennt nicht nur die Sinnhaftigkeit eines über Tauschgerechtigkeit hinausgehenden Konzeptes von sozialer Gerechtigkeit an, er sieht den Hauptteil der Lösung des Gerechtigkeitsproblems gerade durch die geeignete ordnungspolitische Gestaltung des Wettbewerbsprozesses gesichert. […] Notwendigkeit, korrigierend in die Primärverteilung von Einkommen und Vermögen einzugreifen, wie sie sich zunächst „spontan“ auf den Faktor- und Gütermärkten bilden“ (p. 559). 17 Reallocation can only occur in respect of those goods which have been produced at an earlier stage; so, redistribution has to leave enough leeway for free initiatives and economic freedom including freedom of choice and decision (depending on motivation, commitment and performance incentives set by the institutional framework). Eucken is convinced that the ordoliberal competitive order fulfils this criterion of functionality; moreover, it satisfies the criterion of humanity as well: by increasing the overall wealth of a society via an adequate economic policy, the amount of distributional goods and services increases likewise. What is essential here, is to broaden and widen the general participation or sharing in the raising prosperity. Consequently, commutative justice necessarily requires its completion in the form of distributive justice – at least from an ordoliberal point of view. The need for help and un- indebted states of emergency calls for a conception of justice which goes beyond (procedural) justice of exchange and contracts based on the principle of equivalence (i.e. equal give and take, reciprocity, cooperation among equals). Equally important is the principle of subsidiarity gained from Catholic social ethics: According to that, the main emphasis lies on self- responsibility, self-help and communal or club-like help and solidarity (Eucken 1952/2004: pp. 312; Röpke 1942: p. 259; 1944/1949: p. 179; 1958/1961: pp. 249; Rüstow 1955: pp. 54). Inconsistent with the principle of subsidiarity are paternalism and a mentality of patronizing public welfare and care. In consequence, most of the Ordoliberals are highlighting individual responsibility and the importance of security systems while criticizing the evolution of the modern (interventionist) welfare state (cp. Eucken 1952/2004: p. 319; Röpke 1933/1965: p. 175; 1942: p. 261 and p. 271; 1944/1949: pp. 171 and pp. 255; 1958/1961: p. 75, pp. 226 and p. 244; Rüstow 1957: pp. 171 and pp. 178). The redistribution has to act up to certain principles: first of all many Ordoliberals draw a distinct boundary of reallocation; they set a limit of redistribution of income and wealth when economic investment activities are negatively affected; secondly, social policy as the bearer of redistribution should not be carried out in an isolated, selective and ad hoc manner (i.e. constitutional Ordnungspolitik instead of Punktualismus and Prozesspolitik), thirdly, it has to meet the standard of market- conformity (i.e. market-conforming redistribution), fourthly, re-distributive social and income policy should avoid centralistic and interventionist tendencies of the modern welfare state, and lastly, the execution of social policy should be free of discrimination and the granting of privileges. 37 37 Cp. Gröner 1992: pp. 86; Vanberg 2008a und b. 18 3.2. Wilhelm Röpke and Alexander Rüstow: Justice of the Starting Conditions Alexander Rüstow and Wilhelm Röpke are rounding up the ordoliberal theories(!) of justice. It is, therefore, appropriate to say a few words about so called „extended Ordoliberalism‟ or Sociological Neoliberalism: At the heart of Rüstow‟s and Röpke‟s understanding of justice lies so called justice of the starting conditions. In his book Gesellschaftskrisis der Gegenwart, Röpke speaks up for equal starting conditions and equal opportunities. 38 In this context, Röpke pleads for highly progressive inheritance taxes. Additionally, social justice consists of a broad distribution and diffusion of private property, a fight against the concentration of property in the hands of a few people or companies and a fight against diverging income disparities (Röpke 1942: pp. 356; 1958/1961: p. 348). However, Röpke does not rely solely on fair and just starting conditions; rather, he is also an advocate of justice of performance (Leistungsgerechtigkeit) (Röpke 1944/1949: p. 74): the principle of equivalence between performance and counter-performance (guaranteed by the ordoliberal competitive order) is essential as well as a meritocratic societal hierarchy (according to individual performances). In this regard, Röpke opposes (material) egalitarianism (Röpke 1950: pp. 65) and social leveling – although he does not totally condemn socio-political redistribution. He admits that these measurements underlie the principle of market-conformity. Likewise, the ordoliberal concept of justice is highly related – once again – with the topic of societal crisis of the present (Gesellschaftskrisis). In complete accordance with Eucken and Rüstow, Röpke demands (limited) redistribution which removes excessive inequalities. Extreme fortune and income disparities exceeding a certain line endanger social cohesion and societal stability (cp. Böhm 1937: p. 114). Social inequalities are one major source of social upheavals. Social conflicts hinge on the economic (in-)equality between social classes. Hence, in order to avoid self-destructive socio-economic imbalances, Röpke pleads for a distributive policy (Distributionspolitik) in the form of a (more) equal (yet not egalitarian) division of property and income distribution (cp. Röpke 1942: p. 299). The best way to reach this ordoliberal goal is to promote the accumulation of assets and capital of the lower and middle classes. As a result, that kind of social policy will lead to de-proletarianisation and de- massification and it will contribute to solve the social question and the societal crisis of the present. Ordoliberal social policy (a la Röpke and Rüstow) is not only distributive policy; moreover, it is a policy of de-proletarianisation (Politik der Entproletarisierung) as well. 38 For a slightly different position cp. Röpke 1958/1988: pp. 257, p. 260 and p. 269. 19 Here, the main focus lies on enabling emancipation and independency as the basic fundament for autonomous, self-reliant and mature citizens. This emancipatory social policy serves as a surrogate for a lesser compensatory social policy (see also Eucken‟s attempt to overcome the social question in: Eucken 1948 and 2001)! Like Röpke, Rüstow does also emphasize the significance of equal opportunities and justice of the starting conditions (i.e. assimilation 39 of the starting conditions). The societal status should solely depend on each individual‟s meritocratic achievements. While pointing at the weight of equal starting conditions, Rüstow explicitly negates the equality of outcomes (Rüstow 1955: p. 68). In his masterpiece, Ortsbestimmung der Gegenwart, he admits that equality at the beginning (i.e. equality of opportunity) is an indispensable qualification of justice; however, equality at the end (i.e. justice of results; end-state justice (cp. Nozick 2006: pp. 201)) is (relatively) negligible (Rüstow 1957: pp. 90). One major aspect of achieving equality of the starting conditions is via education policy 40 and especially via establishing a system of scholarships (Rüstow 1945/2001: p. 149; see also Röpke 1958/1988: p. 260). 41 A further public task is to radically constrain the law of inheritance. 42 Both facets aspire at combining justice of the starting conditions with the meritocratic performance principle (i.e. Leistungskonkurrenz). 43 Finally, Röpke as well as Rüstow are characterizing (social) justice as a meta-economic value and as a value which is highly correlated with freedom (e.g. Rüstow 1945/2001: p. 153). Thus, justice forms a unified whole, an irenic formula, with liberty! 4. Meta-analytical Comparison In total, the ordoliberal theories(!) of justice consist of several elements and try to incorporate (ex ante) commutative as well as (ex post) distributive justice – referring both to justice of rules as well as justice of outcomes and results. It is a rule based liberalism that emphasizes procedural justice, but at the same time it is by tendency a certain form of end-state and outcome-oriented liberalism as well. It combines commutative justice elements (i.e. Tausch-, 39 When referring to the term equality, Rüstow as well as Röpke are not propagating absolute equality or even egalitarianism; rather, what should be achieved is a relative or an assimilated state of equality. Otherwise, individual freedom would be violated by a considerable degree of coercion and dominion. 40 Cp. also Röpke 1963/1965; Müller-Armack 1960/1981: p. 69; 1972/1981: p. 158. 41 Cp. Rüstow 2001: pp. 83: Here, Rüstow requires equal access to education and its institutions. Exclusion on the basis of lacking financial support should be prohibited. The only pivotal criterion is the performance principle: talents and achievement potentials are the only decisive factors and not the personal social or financial background. 42 The aim is to overcome plutocracy mainly based on inherited inequalities with the help of an aristocratic and feudal inheritance law: every man should ideally be the architect of his own fortune (Rüstow 2001: pp. 83). 43 A just income distribution is one in which all the differences can be ascribed to different degrees of performances of the participants. 20 Vertrags- and Leistungsgerechtigkeit) with distributive justice elements (Verteilungsgerechtigkeit). Karsten (1985: p. 174) seems to be right when he states, that Eucken and other Ordoliberals take a middle position between Nozick‟s, von Hayek‟s and Rawls‟ theory of justice. 44 This eclectic and syncretistic mixture of elements stemming from dissimilar theoretical backgrounds departs from the pure Hayekian notion of commutative justice. One reason for this eclecticism might be that the Ordoliberals aspire to implement an order which is economically and ethically justifiable. Thus, they provide the reader with an integrated approach combining the advantages of competition with concerns for social justice and equity. We can detect the ideal market mechanism with its minimization of economic and political power and with its fairly materialized market price as the result of complete competition. The price mechanism functions as a calculating machine and it operates as an effective communication channel linking producers‟ and consumers‟ needs in a complex and anonymous economy. Furthermore, we can detect the performance-related payment of each factor of production and an income distribution corresponding to each individual market performance, yet not depending on market power structures. Such a competitive order with its unique incentive patterns will ideally enhance the rapid and speedy enforcement and spreading of innovations and it will lead to an increase in productivity promoting the overall wealth of a society (i.e. productivity of freedom). The lower and middle classes will especially benefit from this positive amendment of social welfare. Hence, competitive markets are essentially socially advantageous (cp. Böhm 1933/1964: p. 234: i.e. social productivity of self-interest). Most of the Ordoliberals are quite aware that the primary distribution of income via concurrence and market mechanisms is economically efficient and from a commutative- justice perspective just. But, they are also conscious that the results of fair and (commutatively) just market processes are not necessarily and per se just from a distributive- justice perspective. These outcomes are not compatible with the Kantian principle of universalization and generalization. The income distribution of the markets is at first sight socially blind. In consequence, a correction or redirecting of the income distribution is required – so many Ordoliberals claim. 45 It is necessary to complement the market-steered justice of performance (Leistungsgerechtigkeit) with other norms of justice. Especially the 44 Accordingly, Eucken‟s concept represents not only a synthesis of negative and positive freedom; additionally, it represents a synthesis of Rawls‟ and Nozick‟s theories of justice as well. As Rawls, Eucken‟s primary concern of justice is the basic socioeconomic structure, the question of how to assign fundamental rights, duties, social conditions and institutions, and the care for the worst-off in a society (cp. In der Stunde Null 1979). 45 See also Müller-Armack 1955: S. 85. 21 ordoliberal concern for the worst-off (cp. In der Stunde Null 1979) 46 and the obligatory overcoming of absolute material poverty demands an ex-post facto correction of income distribution. As a result, many Ordoliberals not only command progressive taxation, they also command a minimum configuration of vital resources and the safeguarding of the minimum subsistence level. In other words, the society has to provide basic protection and shelter for the „losers„ of the market game respectively for those individuals and their efforts which are not appreciated and rewarded by market processes (i.e. necessities of life or in German: Bedarfs- or Bedürfnisgerechtigkeit (justice of needs)). This includes security against severe physical privation and certainty of a given minimum of sustenance for all and preclude security of a given standard of life or of the relative position. In this context, Röpke establishes his concept of economic adjustment or adaption interventions (Anpassungsinterventionen; cp. Röpke 1944/1949: p. 376). The goal of such market- conforming interventions is to grant relief and solidary help to the victims of institutional change with its multi-variant processes of adjustment – without violating the market‟s ability to adapt. This kind of redistribution aims at enabling a dignified life. So, questions of redistribution and issues of social or distributive justice are indeed taken into consideration. Nevertheless, the main focus is on commutative justice and the limits of redistribution are highlighted by Eucken, Röpke and Rüstow – especially with regard to the modern welfare state. The best social policy from an ordoliberal perspective is the introduction or maintenance of the competitive order complemented by anti-poverty measures and basic (mandatory) social insurance systems. In addition, the distributive-justice concept of Ordoliberalism is quite rudimentary, elementary and in a certain way vague and indeterminate – a revision in the sense of modification and actualization is applicable and could incorporate for example societal rights of participation and inclusion (i.e. Mitwirkungs- or Teilhaberechte)). 47 The fundamental difference to the Hayekian concept of justice is the ordoliberal incorporation of distributive-justice elements – although they are not in the centre of the ordoliberal theories – and the slightly or at least not completely neglected outcome-oriented perspective on social policy. 48 This perspective, however, does not include equal, in the sense of egalitarian, results. 46 I.e. market economy with a conscience: in order to protect the economically weak and to safeguard freedom, unrestrained capitalism must give way to responsible and limited market-conforming economic interventions. 47 Cp. Ulrich 2008 and Goldschmidt 2011. 48 A further examination question could be to investigate whether this slightly outcome-oriented perspective of Ordoliberalism is compatible with Amartya Sen‟s approach (cp. Sen‟s recently published book on justice: Sen 2009). Sen‟s own approach to justice is a comparative and relational one. It is realization-focused respectively based on comparisons and comparative assessments and it focuses on the advancement or retreat of justice. The main question underlying his theory is: What (international) reforms do we need to make the world a bit less 22 Von Hayek, on the other side, completely rejects social and distributive justice as well as outcome-oriented state interventions. His focus is on formal rules and commutative justice as characteristics of a rule of law government instead of an arbitrary government (Hayek 1944/2007: p. 113; see also von Hayek‟s model constitution in: Hayek 1979). As stated above, von Hayek is convinced that a free economy can simply obtain commutative justice, while distributive justice is characteristic of organizations and socialism. It is the kind of justice prevalent in military and bureaucratic organizations and in a command-society, particularly in a totalitarian system of un-freedom, slavery and personal despotism (Hayek 1962/2008: pp. 642). Remarkable is the fact that the just mentioned Hayek-quotes are borrowed from von Hayek‟s inaugural lecture at the University of Freiburg in which von Hayek stresses the parallels in thinking of his own account and the ordoliberal one. Von Hayek is here – when he refers to social justice – either indirectly and implicitly criticizing Eucken et al. or he is simply not aware of the underlying subtle differences between Ordoliberalism and the position held by him. Here, it is necessary to add two (preliminary) comments for the avoidance of doubt and in order to evade misunderstandings: first of all, the essay clearly pursues a (descriptive-) comparative goal elaborating the points of fine differences inside neoliberalism. With this contrasting purpose in mind, it seems legitimate to emphasize and highlight the gaps and to stress the points of refined distinction as a rhetorical device. However, this does not mean, that the positions held by von Hayek, Eucken, Rüstow and Röpke are mutually incompatible. To state it clearly: A sharp contrast and a diametrical opposite cannot be proved. To the contrary, a wide range of parallels do exist – particularly between (the late) Franz Böhm, a further member of the Freiburg School, Eucken and von Hayek. 49 Moreover, both strands of neoliberalism can be regarded as predecessors (and representatives) of modern Constitutional Economics and they gave fresh impetus to New Institutional Economics (cp. the works of Vanberg 2008a; 2008b and Wohlgemuth 2008). Nevertheless, the differences do not have to unjust? According to Sen, actual assessments of freedoms and capabilities as well as assessments of outcomes and realizations are required as a major pre-condition to make a choice between alternative policies. Sen sets his own approach apart from a contractual or arrangement focus approach to justice which aims at identifying perfectly just institutional arrangements for a society and which is based on transcendental justice. 49 Especially Böhm‟s concept of private law society closely resembles von Hayek‟s Great Society. See for more information on the personal relationship (not friendship!) between von Hayek and Eucken their correspondence (Hayek 1939-1950). Remarkable is the stepwise personal alienation between von Hayek and so called Economic Humanism à la Rüstow and Röpke: While von Hayek, Rüstow and Röpke were friends at an earlier age; they gradually became opponents and even enemies in their second half of life. Rüstow even called von Hayek a libertarian paleo-liberal (see Hennecke 2008: p. 149; Karabelas 2010: pp. 88; compare also the debates of the Mont Pelerin Society in Plickert 2008). As a result, the variations between von Hayek and Rüstow/Röpke are more severe compared to those between von Hayek and Böhm/Eucken. In this case, I favor the thesis of gradualism ranging from von Hayek‟s evolutionary liberalism via Ordoliberalism of the Freiburg School (Böhm and Eucken) to Sociological Neoliberalism/Economic Humanism (Röpke and Rüstow). 23 be obliterated; the distinctions, even those which are delicate and gradual, have to be recognized. 50 Secondly, there is no unified ordoliberal theory of justice or a homogenous and unitary understanding of justice; rather, (more or less) individual answers to the social question and to social justice exist, no doubt. Moreover, a complete accordance between Eucken, Rüstow and Röpke is far from certain. 51 But, and that is essential, both Eucken and Rüstow/Röpke are integrating re-distributive elements into their theories of justice. Here, a common ground and a similarity between Eucken, Rüstow and Röpke can be reached. At the same time, this is also the point of departure and demarcation comparing Eucken, Rüstow and Röpke on the one hand and von Hayek on the other hand: The best social policy, according to the members of the Freiburg School of Law and Economics, is the introduction and preservation of the competitive order. They are favoring the integration of the question of social justice into their concept of Ordnungspolitik. The social question is regarded as a result of insufficient competition, as a result of a state of re-feudalization (Vermachtung) and as a failure of the state to implement and maintain the institutional framework. Social question, social justice and the question of private power in a free society are, therefore, interlinked (so far, the approaches of Ordoliberalism and von Hayek are more or less equivalent). In addition, Ordoliberalism (in the broader sense) incorporates a (slightly) outcome-oriented perspective on social policy. Eucken‟s regulatory principle of income policy, for example, aims at correcting the results of market processes (i.e. income (re-) distribution via progressive taxation): Urgent needs and a minimum subsistence level have to be guaranteed via a state- run and re-distributive social policy. Moreover, Eucken does not condemn worker participation, trade unions and state-run welfare institutions complementary to private insurance companies. In special circumstances, even minimum wages are allowed (cp. Eucken‟s regulative principles incorporating e.g. the internalization of external effects, a redistributive income policy (i.e. progressive taxation) in order to correct socially unacceptable market outcomes, and the setting of minimum wages). Von Hayek, on the contrary, rejects any outcome-oriented state interventions and he logically rejects (the ordoliberal) synthesis of commutative and distributive justice. Von Hayek is highly critical of redistribution via progressive taxation and he abhors minimum wages: according to him, a minimum subsistence level has to be guaranteed (i.e. securing one‟s 50 Just as von Hayek is not a member of the Chicago School, he is not a member of Ordoliberalism and the Freiburg School of Law and Economics. 51 Differences between Rüstow, Röpke and Eucken refer to the topic of equality of opportunity/justice of the starting conditions and education policy. Both are completely lacking in Eucken‟s writings. All have in common the integration of re-distributive elements (i.e. distributive justice elements are already laid down by Eucken, however, these elements play a more prominent role within the theories of justice developed by Rüstow and Röpke), the topic of Gesellschaftskrisis and the aim of overcoming the problem of socio-economic power. 24 livelihood), however without intervening in market processes and without (ex post) correcting market results. He clearly differentiates between securing one‟s livelihood, a minimum subsistence level and protection against severe deprivation (i.e. minimum income) on the one hand and minimum wages on the other hand (cp. e.g. Hayek 1960 pp. 285; 1960/1988: pp. 406; 1976: p. 87 52 ). Insofar, von Hayek‟s argument is by far more consistent and stringent – compared with the ordoliberal ones. His theory of justice rests clearly on commutative justice while excluding all forms of distributive justice. The ordoliberal mixture of distributive and commutative justice-elements, to the contrary, (slightly) opens the gateway for special interest groups and it provides the state with discretionary leeway for economic policy interventions. It is now possible to sum up the parallels and differences in the theories of justice: both Ordoliberalism and von Hayek are emphasizing Ordnungs- instead of Prozesspolitik, both are relying on competition on the merits, the principle of market conformity and the (Kantian) private law society with its freedom of privileges and discrimination; more importantly, both are warning against the dangers of the welfare state (cp. e.g. Röpke 1958/1988; Hayek 1960/1988) and the dangers of socialism and totalitarianism. Moreover, both prefer the principle of subsidiarity, self-responsibility, self-help and communal or club-like help and solidarity instead of (forced) national assistance and state-run welfare organizations. All these commonalities are due to the fact that both Ordoliberalism and von Hayek are – at least in their early years – fighting all kinds of totalitarian ideologies. They are both pursuing the same goals and fighting on similar frontline positions. However, the applied means and the adopted specific route towards the (shared) goals are slightly different. Among the differences are: 1. Von Hayek’s problem of knowledge vs. the ordoliberal problem of power: Von Hayek regards markets as processes of coordination of decentralized and incomplete knowledge responsible for the allocation of factors of productivity. He supposes a division of labor as well as a division of knowledge. In this regard, market mechanisms are superior and gain advantage in increasing the overall wealth of a society and thus, reaching the goal of (commutative) justice. The ordoliberal approach is dissimilar: they are approaching justice via the problem of power and the topic of Gesellschaftskrisis: According to Ordoliberalism social justice, the social question and the reduction and prevention of the misuse of socio-economic powers are highly interlinked: Re-feudalization (among others) is one major source of injustice; 2. Von Hayek’s ‘impossibility theorem’ (it is simply not feasible to reach a unique, consensual and generalizable definition of positive (distributive) justice) vs. the ordoliberal 52 In the third volume of Law, Legislation and Liberty (Hayek 1979: pp. 93 and pp. 141), von Hayek opposes any politically determined wage structure and state-run income policies (i.e. minimum wages, etc.); instead, he favors the “assurance of a certain flat minimum income” (i.e. minimum subsistence level; p. 143). 25 multi-faceted concept of justice respectively commutative vs. distributive justice: Von Hayek clearly opposes the redistribution by progressive taxation and favors proportional taxation (unlike Ordoliberalism 53 ); he clearly opposes the ex post correction of market results via fiscal policy and all other measures related to distributive justice (unlike some representatives of Ordoliberalism); he clearly opposes (interventionist) social policy and state-run social security systems 54 (unlike some Ordoliberals), which will lead to a totalitarian economic dictatorship (according to von Hayek, all distributive justice measures are compulsory tools of egalitarian and socialist redistribution); he neglects the moment of Gesellschaftskrisis which is at the heart of Ordoliberalism in the broader sense (especially Rüstow and Röpke aim at the de-proletarianization, de-massification and the disempowerment of interest groups; therefore, they aim at an emancipatory social policy with a broad distribution of assets and an adequate education policy); he opposes the principle of equality of opportunities and the ordoliberal concept of the starting conditions (unlike Rüstow and Röpke; cp. Hennecke 2008: pp. 113 and pp. 121). 55 In short: distributive justice-elements can only be found in the ordoliberal version(s) of neoliberalism. 5. Concluding Remarks As stated in the introduction, variations and disparities between von Hayek and Ordoliberalism can be found on diverse levels: i.e. philosophy of science, setting dissimilar priorities, social philosophy, genesis of norms, and notion of freedom. In the current paper I have analyzed another potential dimension of differences – which is by the way interlinked with the opposed conceptions of genesis of norms: the ordoliberal and the Hayekian theories of justice with its differing setting of priorities: i.e. von Hayek‟s commutative justice concept vs. the ordoliberal mixture of commutative and distributive justice. The Ordoliberals believe that true social benefits of their competitive order derive inherently from the long-term stability of competitive markets by suppressing arbitrary and disorderly political and economic power, by eliminating monopolistic and oligopolistic strumctures and by the ceaseless functioning of individual freedom and competition (cp. Rittershausen 2007: p. 9). Contrary to von Hayek who is convinced that the weasel-word „social‟ itself is an 53 Cp. Eucken 1952/2004: pp. 300: „Sie [die Progression der Einkommenssteuer] soll den Verteilungsprozeß im Rahmen der Wettbewerbsordnung korrigieren“ (here: p. 301). 54 What is required – according to von Hayek – is an abolition of the government monopoly of services and the privatization and decentralization of social insurances, education, etc (Hayek 1979: p. 147). 55 The concept of equality of opportunity/equal starting conditions is an “illusory ideal”, as stated by von Hayek (Hayek 1976: p. 10 and pp. 84), since all still remaining handicaps and disadvantages must be removed by a powerful and coercive government; equality of opportunity is (only) important in cases of appointments to public offices (i.e. talent and skill oriented) and schooling of minors (p. 84). 26 excuse to disguise a collectivist and, hence, an anti-social agenda, many Ordoliberals take the view that market-conforming interventions as well as re-distributive „interventions‟ are indispensable in order to overcome the (new) social question. 56 As a consequence, they implement regulating principles which are designed – on the one hand – to stabilize and sustain the competitive order and – on the other hand – to correct certain shortcomings of the market (in modern terms: market failures). To these belong the stringent control of monopoly power, the public regulation of severe supply side anomalies such as mass unemployment, the redistribution of income through a progressive tax system and last but not least the corrections of socio-economic externalities due to large discrepancies between short-term profits and personal self-interests and the long-term common or collective good. Especially the essays originated from the interdisciplinary cooperation within the Freiburg resistance circles against National-socialism contain certain re-distributive measurements and social policy advices (cp. In der Stunde Null 1979; Dietze/Eucken/Lampe 1941/1942 and 1943/2008): The aim of a Christian based society is a functioning and humane socio- economic order. Such an order strives for fostering self-responsibility and proactive individual initiative. It rests on small and medium sized companies and it precludes the ruling of interest and para-governmental rent seeking groups. However, equally important is the prevention of unjust distributions of income, assets and property. It is the explicit goal of social policy to provide for humane employment with equally just payment, to avoid exploitation, mass poverty and unemployment. Eucken, for example, endorses supply anomaly interventions by subsidizing minimum wages and by guaranteeing a minimum subsistence level (Eucken 1952/2004: pp. 185, pp. 303 and pp. 321). Especially important are progressive taxes. Moreover, he – in complete accordance with Constantin von Dietze and Adolf Lampe, both members of the Freiburg (resistance) Circles – pleads for equal market positions with regard to the exercise of power and influence between employers and employees (cp. Eucken 1946/1999: p. 21 and 1952/2004: p. 322). Only when the status of a balance of power has been reached on labor markets and when employers and employees are able to negotiate their working conditions at an equal level and with true freedom of contract, is it possible to minimize exploitation, reduce asymmetric, patriarchal and paternalistic employer-employee relationships, decrease dependencies and the misuse of power and realize social peace within a society. Therefore, it is one key element of social policy to support labor 56 For Eucken and others, social policies are only acceptable in so far as they do not disrupt or infringe upon the primacy of stable prices in a perfectly competitive marketplace and only in so far as they are not influenced by biased interest groups and “limited in scope to truly social-fabric-ripping vagaries” (Rittershausen 2007: pp. 12). Not acceptable from an ordoliberal point of view is a Müller-Armack-like anti-cyclical policy where the state engages in vaguely defined business cycle management in order to cool off credit booms. 27 unions until they are equally powerful as the federation of employers or to downgrade the level of power of employers until they have just as little power as labor unions. Both parties of the labor market should be equally powerful – provided that they do not dominate economic processes and that they do not exert pressure on political decision making processes. It is a remarkable fact that Ordoliberalism connects its theories of justice with its elaborations on liberty and power (cp. also Forst 2007: pp. 270). With all these dissimilarities in mind it is possible to draw a distinction within neoliberalism (i.e. in total, neoliberalism is no monolithic block): Von Hayek‟s evolutionary liberalism (and co-generic types of neoliberalism like Buchanan‟s and Vanberg‟s constitutional economics) have to be separated from German Ordoliberalism in general and the Freiburg School of Economics and Sociological Neoliberalism in particular. In addition, they challenge the stimulating thesis that von Hayek can be described as an Ordoliberal (cp. Kolev 2010). Thus, the work of Ordoliberalism should not be viewed through Hayekian lenses only; it deserves an economic-ethical perspective as well! References: BECKER, Helmut Paul (1965): Die soziale Frage im Neoliberalismus. Analyse und Kritik; Heidelberg, F.H. Kerle Verlag. BÖHM, Franz (1933/1964): Wettbewerb und Monopolkampf. Eine Untersuchung zur Frage des wirtschaftlichen Kampfrechts und zur Frage der rechtlichen Struktur der geltenden Wirtschaftsordnung; Berlin, Carl Heymanns Verlag. - (1937): Die Ordnung der Wirtschaft als geschichtliche Aufgabe und rechtsschöpferische Leistung; Stuttgart, Verlag von W. Kohlhammer. - (1966/1980): Privatrechtsgesellschaft und Marktwirtschaft in: Böhm: Freiheit und Ordnung in der Marktwirtschaft; Baden-Baden, Nomos; pp. 105-168. BÖNKER, Frank/WAGENER, Hans-Jürgen (2001): Hayek and Eucken on the State and Market Economy in: Labrousse, Agnès/Weisz, Jean-Daniel (eds.): Institutional Economics in France and Germany. German Ordoliberalism versus the French Regulation School; Berlin, Springer; pp. 183-199. DIETZE, Constantin von/EUCKEN, Walter/LAMPE, Adolf (probably 1941/1942): Volkswirtschaftsfibel/ Nationalökonomische Fibel in: Nachlass Popitz (BA NL 1262/87), Koblenz, Bundesarchiv. - (1943/2008): Wirtschafts- und Sozialordnung in: Goldschmidt, Nils/Wohlgemuth, Michael (eds.): Grundtexte zur Freiburger Tradition der Ordnungsökonomik; Tübingen, Mohr Siebeck; pp. 99-115. ERHARD, Ludwig/MÜLLER-ARMACK, Alfred (1972): Soziale Marktwirtschaft. Ordnung der Zukunft. Manifest ‟72; Frankfurt, Ullstein Verlag. EUCKEN, Walter (1946/1999): Über die Gesamtrichtung der Wirtschaftspolitik in: Eucken: Ordnungspolitik; Münster, LIT Verlag; pp. 1-24. - (1948): Die soziale Frage in: Ludwig Erhard Stiftung (ed.): Grundtexte zur Sozialen Marktwirtschaft. Zeugnisse aus zweihundert Jahren ordnungspolitischer Diskussion; Stuttgart, Fischer; pp. 329-339. 28 - (1950/1996): Deutschland vor und nach der Währungsreform in: Schneider, Jürgen/ Harbrecht, Wolfgang (eds.): Wirtschaftsordnung und Wirtschaftspolitik in Deutschland (1933-1993); Stuttgart, Franz Steiner Verlag; pp. 327-360. - (1952/2004): Grundsätze der Wirtschaftspolitik; Tübingen, Mohr Siebeck. - (1953): Wettbewerb, Monopol und Unternehmer; Bad Nauheim, Vita Verlag. - (2001): Wirtschaftsmacht und Wirtschaftsordnung – Londoner Vorträge zur Wirtschaftspolitik und zwei Beiträge zur Antimonopolpolitik; Münster, LIT Verlag. FORST, Rainer (2007): Das Recht auf Rechtfertigung. Elemente einer konstruktivistischen Theorie der Gerechtigkeit; Frankfurt, Suhrkamp. GOLDSCHMIDT, Nils (2011): Vom Glück und von Gärten. Moderne Ordnungsökonomik und die normativen Grundlagen der Gesellschaft in: Caspari, Volker/Schefold, Bertram (eds.): Wohin steuert die ökonomische Wissenschaft? Ein Methodenstreit in der Volkswirtschaftslehre; Frankfurt, Campus Verlag. GRÖNER, Helmut (1992): Walter Eucken – Wegbereiter der Ordnungspolitik in: Walter Eucken Institut (ed.): Ordnung in Freiheit; Tübingen, Mohr Siebeck; pp., 79-88. HAYEK, Friedrich August von (1939-1950): Nachlass F.A. von Hayek, NL Hayek, F.A. von Hayek Papers; Stanford, Hoover Institution Archives. - (1944/2007): The Road to Serfdom; Chicago, University of Chicago Press. - (1960): The Constitution of Liberty; London, Routledge & Kegan Paul. - (1960/1988): Freiheit im Wohlfahrtsstaat in: Hohmann et al. (eds.): Grundtexte zur Sozialen Marktwirtschaft Band 2: Das Soziale in der Sozialen Marktwirtschaft; Stuttgart, Gustav Fischer Verlag; pp. 387-409. - (1962/2008): Wirtschaft, Wissenschaft und Politik in: Goldschmidt, Nils/Wohlgemuth, Michael (eds.): Grundtexte zur Freiburger Tradition der Ordnungsökonomik; Tübingen, Mohr Siebeck; pp. 637-651. - (1966/1996): Eine sich selbst bildende Ordnung für die Gesellschaft in: Kerber, Wolfgang (ed.): Die Anmaßung von Wissen. Neue Freiburger Studien; Tübingen, Mohr Siebeck; pp. 262-266. - (1968/2002): Competition as a Discovery Procedure in: Quarterly Journal of Austrian Economics 5/3; pp. 9-23. - (1970/1996): Die Irrtümer des Konstruktivismus und die Grundlagen legitimer Kritik gesellschaftlicher Gebilde in: Kerber, Wolfgang (ed.): Die Anmaßung von Wissen. Neue Freiburger Studien; Tübingen, Mohr Siebeck; pp. 16-36. - (1973): Law, Legislation and Liberty. A new statement of the liberal principles of justice and political economy Vol. 1: Rules and Order; London, Routledge & Kegan Paul. - (1973/1996): Die Erhaltung des liberalen Gedankengutes in: Kerber, Wolfgang (ed.): Die Anmaßung von Wissen. Neue Freiburger Studien; Tübingen, Mohr Siebeck; pp. 249-261. - (1974/1996): Die Anmaßung von Wissen (Pretence of Knowledge) in: Kerber, Wolfgang (ed.): Die Anmaßung von Wissen. Neue Freiburger Studien; Tübingen, Mohr Siebeck; pp. 3- 15. - (1976): Law, Legislation and Liberty Volume 2. The Mirage of Social Justice; London, Routledge & Kegan Paul. - (1976/1996a): Der Atavismus »sozialer Gerechtigkeit« in: Kerber, Wolfgang (ed.): Die Anmaßung von Wissen. Neue Freiburger Studien; Tübingen, Mohr Siebeck; pp. 181-192. - (1976/1996b): Die Illusion der sozialen Gerechtigkeit in: Kerber, Wolfgang (ed.): Die Anmaßung von Wissen. Neue Freiburger Studien; Tübingen, Mohr Siebeck; pp. 193-203. - (1978/1996a): Die drei Quellen der menschlichen Werte in: Kerber, Wolfgang (ed.): Die Anmaßung von Wissen. Neue Freiburger Studien; Tübingen, Mohr Siebeck; pp. 37-75. - (1978/1996b): Liberalismus in: Kerber, Wolfgang (ed.): Die Anmaßung von Wissen. Neue Freiburger Studien; Tübingen, Mohr Siebeck; pp. 216-248. 29 - (1979): Law, Legislation and Liberty Vol. 3: The Political Order of a Free People; London, Routledge & Kegan Paul. - (1979/1996): Wissenschaft und Sozialismus in: Kerber, Wolfgang (ed.): Die Anmaßung von Wissen. Neue Freiburger Studien; Tübingen, Mohr Siebeck; pp. 267-277. - (1983/1996): Evolution und spontane Ordnung in: Kerber, Wolfgang (ed.): Die Anmaßung von Wissen. Neue Freiburger Studien; Tübingen, Mohr Siebeck; pp. 102-113. HECKER, Christian (2008): Lohn- und Preisgerechtigkeit. Historische Rückblicke und aktuelle Perspektiven unter besonderer Berücksichtigung der christlichen Soziallehren; Marburg, Metropolis-Verlag. HENNECKE, Hans Jörg (2000): Friedrich August von Hayek. Die Tradition der Freiheit; Düsseldorf, Verlag Wirtschaft und Finanzen. - (2008): Friedrich August von Hayek zur Einführung; Hamburg, Junius. IN DER STUNDE NULL (1979): Die Denkschrift des Freiburger „Bonhoeffer-Kreises“: Politische Gemeinschaftsordnung. Ein Versuch zur Selbstbestimmung des christlichen Gewissens in den politischen Nöten unserer Zeit; Tübingen, Mohr Siebeck. KARABELAS, Iris (2010): Freiheit statt Sozialismus. Rezeption und Bedeutung Friedrich August von Hayeks in der Bundesrepublik; Frankfurt, Suhrkamp. KARSTEN, Siegfried (1985): Eucken‟s „Social Market Economy‟ and Its Test in Post-War West Germany: The Economist as Social Philosopher Developed Ideas That Paralleled Progressive Thoughts in America in: American Journal of Economics and Sociology, Vol. 44, No. 2; pp. 169-183. KLUMP, Rainer/WÖRSDÖRFER, Manuel (2010): An Ordoliberal Interpretation of Adam Smith in: ORDO 61; pp. 29-51. KOLEV, Stefan (2008): Macht und Wissen als Determinanten: Zur Rolle des Staates in der Wirtschaftspolitik bei Walter Eucken und Friedrich August von Hayek; retrieved October 1, 2010 from: www.hwwi.de/uploads/tx_wilpubdb/HWWI_Research_Paper_5-4.pdf. - (2010): Hayek as an Ordo-Liberal; HWWI Research Paper 5-11; retrieved October 1, 2010 from: www.hwwi.org/uploads/tx_wilpubdb/HWWI_Research_Paper_5-11.pdf. KÜLP, Bernhard (2000): Walter Eucken und die soziale Frage in: Külp, Bernhard/Vanberg, Viktor (eds.): Freiheit und wettbewerbliche Ordnung. Gedenkband zur Erinnerung an Walter Eucken; Freiburg, Haufe Verlag; pp. 155-176. MÜLLER-ARMACK, Alfred (1955): Wirtschaftspolitik in der sozialen Marktwirtschaft in: Boarman, Patrick (ed.): Der Christ und die soziale Marktwirtschaft; Stuttgart, W. Kohlhammer Verlag; pp. 75-99. - (1959/1976): Die Soziale Marktwirtschaft nach einem Jahrzehnt ihrer Erprobung in: Müller- Armack: Wirtschaftsordnung und Wirtschaftspolitik. Studien und Konzepte zur Sozialen Marktwirtschaft und zur Europäischen Integration; Bern, Haupt; pp. 251-265. - (1960/1981): Die zweite Phase der Sozialen Marktwirtschaft: Ihre Ergänzung durch das Leitbild einer neuen Gesellschaftspolitik in: Ludwig Erhard Stiftung (ed.): Grundtexte zur Sozialen Marktwirtschaft. Zeugnisse aus zweihundert Jahren ordnungspolitischer Diskussion; Stuttgart, Fischer; pp. 63-78. - (1972/1981): Die Soziale Marktwirtschaft und ihre Widersacher in: Müller-Armack: Genealogie der Sozialen Marktwirtschaft; Bern, Haupt; pp. 147-160. NOZICK, Robert (2006): Anarchie. Staat. Utopia; München, Olzog Verlag. NUTZINGER, Hans G./HECKER, Christian (2008): Gerechtigkeit in der Ökonomie – ein unlösbarer Widerspruch? in: Leviathan 4/2008; pp. 543-575. PIES, Ingo (2001): Eucken und von Hayek im Vergleich. Zur Aktualisierung der ordnungspolitischen Konzeption; Mohr Siebeck, Tübingen. PLICKERT, Philipp (2008): Wandlungen des Neoliberalismus. Eine Studie zu Entwicklung und Ausstrahlung der „Mont Pèlerin Society“; Lucius & Lucius, Stuttgart. 30 POPPER, Karl R. (1957/2003): Die offene Gesellschaft und ihre Feinde. Band I: Der Zauber Platons; Tübingen, Mohr Siebeck. - (1958/2003): Die offene Gesellschaft und ihre Feinde. Band II: Falsche Propheten: Hegel, Marx und die Folgen; Tübingen, Mohr Siebeck. QUAAS, Friedrun (2000): Soziale Marktwirtschaft. Wirklichkeit und Verfremdung eines Konzepts; Bern, Verlag Paul Haupt. RENNER, Andreas (1999/2000): Die zwei „Neoliberalismen“ in: Fragen der Freiheit 256; retrieved July 11, 2010 from www.tristan-abromeit.de/pdf/MdB%20Gruene%20Anhang%20I.pdf. RITTERSHAUSEN, Johannes R.B. (2007): The Postwar West German Economic Transition: From Ordoliberalism to Keynesianism; Köln, IWP Discussion Paper No. 2007/1, Institut für Wirtschaftspolitik. RÖPKE, Wilhelm (1933/1965): Epochenwende? in: Röpke: Fronten der Freiheit. Wirtschaft – Internationale Ordnung – Politik. Eine Auslese aus dem Gesamtwerk; Stuttgart, Seewald Verlag; pp. 167-178. - (1942): Die Gesellschaftskrisis der Gegenwart; Erlenbach, Rentsch. - (1944/1949): Civitas Humana. Grundfragen der Gesellschafts- und Wirtschaftsreform; Erlenbach, Rentsch. - (1950): Mass und Mitte; Erlenbach, Rentsch. - (1958/1961): Jenseits von Angebot und Nachfrage; Erlenbach, Rentsch. - (1958/1988): Gefahren des Wohlfahrtsstaates in: Hohmann, Karl et al. (eds.): Grundtexte zur Sozialen Marktwirtschaft. Das Soziale in der Sozialen Marktwirtschaft; Stuttgart, Gustav Fischer Verlag; pp. 253-270 - (1963/1965): Die Stellung der Wissenschaft in der Industriegesellschaft in: Röpke: Fronten der Freiheit. Wirtschaft – Internationale Ordnung – Politik. Eine Auslese aus dem Gesamtwerk; Stuttgart, Seewald Verlag; pp. 214-227. RÜSTOW, Alexander (1945/2001): Das Versagen des Wirtschaftsliberalismus; Marburg, Metropolis. - (1955): Wirtschaftsethische Probleme der sozialen Marktwirtschaft in: Boarman, Patrick (ed.): Der Christ und die soziale Marktwirtschaft; Stuttgart, Kohlhammer Verlag; pp. 53-74. - (1957): Ortsbestimmung der Gegenwart. Eine universalgeschichtliche Kulturkritik. Dritter Band. Herrschaft oder Freiheit?; Erlenbach, Rentsch. - (2001): Die Religion der Marktwirtschaft; Münster, LIT Verlag. SALLY, Razeen (1996): Ordoliberalism and the Social Market: Classical Political Economy from Germany in: New Political Economy Vol. 1, Issue 2; pp. 1-18. SEN, Amartya (2009): The Idea of Justice; Cambridge, Harvard University Press. STREIT, Manfred E./WOHLGEMUTH, Michael (2000a): Walter Eucken und Friedrich A. von Hayek: Initiatoren der Ordnungsökonomik in: Külp, Bernhard/Vanberg, Viktor (eds.): Freiheit und wettbewerbliche Ordnung. Gedenkband zur Erinnerung an Walter Eucken; Freiburg, Haufe Verlag; pp. 461-498. - (2000b): The Market Economy and the State. Hayekian and Ordoliberal Conceptions in: Koslowski, Peter (ed.): The Theory of Capitalism in the German Economic Tradition. Historism, Ordo-Liberalism, Critical Theory, Solidarism; Heidelberg, Springer; pp. 224-271. ULRICH, Peter (2008): Integrative Economic Ethics. Foundations of a Civilized Market Economy; Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. VANBERG, Viktor (2006): Marktwirtschaft und Gerechtigkeit. Zu F.A. Hayeks Kritik am Konzept der „sozialen Gerechtigkeit“ in: Held, Martin/Kubon-Gilke, Gisela/Sturn, Richard (eds.): Soziale Sicherung in Marktgesellschaften; Marburg, Metropolis Verlag; pp. 39-69. - (2008a): Der konsensorientierte Ansatz der konstitutionellen Ökonomik in: Vanberg, Viktor: Wettbewerb und Regelordnung; Tübingen, Mohr Siebeck; pp. 23-48. - (2008b): Die normativen Grundlagen von Ordnungspolitik in: Vanberg, Viktor: Wettbewerb 31 und Regelordnung; Tübingen, Mohr Siebeck; pp. 49-67. VOGT, Markus (1999/2009): Soziale Interaktion und Gerechtigkeit in: Handbuch der Wirtschaftsethik Bd. 1.1.: Verhältnisbestimmung von Wirtschaft und Ethik. Konstitutive Bauelemente moderner Wirtschaftsethik. Grundfragen ethischer Rationalität in einer globalen Welt; Berlin, Berlin University Press; pp. 284-309. WATRIN, Christian (2000): Staatsaufgaben: Die Sicht Walter Euckens und Friedrich A. von Hayeks in: Külp, Bernhard/Vanberg, Viktor (eds.): Freiheit und wettbewerbliche Ordnung. Gedenkband zur Erinnerung an Walter Eucken; Freiburg, Haufe Verlag; pp. 323-343. WÖRSDÖRFER, Manuel (2010): Ordoliberalism and the Evolution of Norms; Normative Orders Working Paper 07/2010; available at: http://publikationen.ub.uni- frankfurt.de/volltexte/2010/8701/pdf/Ordoliberalism_and_the_Evolution_of_Norms.pdf. - (2011): Die normativen und wirtschaftsethischen Grundlagen des Ordoliberalismus; Frankfurt. - (forthcoming): Individual and Regulatory Ethics: An Economic-Ethical and Theoretical- Historical Analysis of Ordoliberalism. WOHLGEMUTH, Michael (2008): A European Social Model of State-Market Relations. The Ethics of Competition from a “Neo-liberal” Perspective in: zfwu 9/1; pp. 69-87. work_d7ed3f2iwnan3im27qe7qsb6xy ---- Social Capital and Social Justice Procedia Economics and Finance 8 ( 2014 ) 246 – 253 2212-5671 © 2014 The Authors. Published by Elsevier B.V. Open access under CC BY-NC-ND license. Selection and peer-review under responsibility of the Organizing Committee of ESPERA 2013 doi: 10.1016/S2212-5671(14)00087-2 ScienceDirect 1st International Conference 'Economic Scientific Research - Theoretical, Empirical and Practical Approaches', ESPERA 2013 Social capital and social justice Emil Dingaa* aCentre for Financial and Monetary Research „Victor Slăvescu”, Calea 13 Septembrie 13, 050711,Bucharest, Romania Abstract This paperaims toanalyse the issueof implementing the justicein a societywithdemocratic rules,taking into account the social capital structure. To thisend, a typology of the social capital isproposedand examined, getting to a qualitativetypologyof the social in sixspecieswhichare thengrouped into threepairsbased onthe relationship betweenindividuationand socialization phenomena. In thiscontext,social justiceprinciples and criteriaare evaluatedand correlated withthe social capitaltypology, extractingconclusions abouthowa practicable social justicemay be boththe source andthe destination othe social capitaldynamics. Finally, the paperproposes somenotabledistinctionsbetweensocial justice andsocial rightness, basedalsoon theproposedtypology of the social capital. © 2014 The Authors. Published by Elsevier B.V. Selection and peer-review under responsibility of the Organizing Committee of ESPERA 2013. Keywords:social capital, social justice, social rightness, social distribution 1. Structure of the social capital If we imagine our planet (which is limited from any point of view) as a circle, then a model of its sustainability may be seen as an equilateral triangle inscribed in that circle (figure 1): * Corresponding author. Tel.: +40722588863; E-mail address: emildinga2004@yahoo.com © 2014 The Authors. Published by Elsevier B.V. Open access under CC BY-NC-ND license. Selection and peer-review under responsibility of the Organizing Committee of ESPERA 2013 Available online at www.sciencedirect.com http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1016/S2212-5671(14)00087-2&domain=pdf http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/ http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/ 247 Emil Dinga / Procedia Economics and Finance 8 ( 2014 ) 246 – 253 1.1. Types of capital and the societal paradigm Fig. 1.Paradigm of planet Earth sustainability It is obvious that making any side of the triangle shorter by extending the others is a deviation from sustainability. The paradigm of sustainability is an artefact; it has not been invented by nature. Although this statement may be strongly polemical, in our opinion, nature invented only the survival, which is not the same thing as the sustainability. The difference between survival and sustainability consists in the teleological character of sustainability (therefore, about sustainability we may speak only accepting the presence of the cultural beings). Actually, the history of the human society is the very history of the domination of one form or another of capital. Each category of dominant capital imposed its own logic principle of movement, constructed its own actional paradigm and generated its own social formation (table1): Table 1.General picture of the association of the type of capital with the societal paradigm T y p e o f c a p i t a l (F u n d a m e n t a l o r c r u c i a l r e s o u r c e) Natural Cultural (Artefactual) Physical Non-physical Substanti al (tangible) Financial (intangibl e) Individual Socia l Biologica l Intellectual Mora l The logic principle Methodological collectivism Methodological individualism Methodological holism The actional paradigm Stationarity Optimality Sustainability The societal establishment Naturalism Capitalism ? Therefore, the necessity (under the sanction of extinction), for the human society, to access the paradigm of sustainability by replacing the paradigm of optimality seems to have no other alternative 1.2. Want is the social capital? In general, we will name capital any entity (either substantial or informational) which brings an advantage of any kind to the holder of that entity. It is of no importance if that advantage is current or future. According to Figure 1 above, there may be six distinct (fundamental) type of capital: a) natural capital (for instance, a river); b) substantial capital (for instance, a house); c) financial capital (for instance, amonetaryincome); d) biologic capital (for instance, the health state of an individual); e) intellectual capital (for instance, the educational level of a person); f) social capital (for instance, human rights institutionalization). These types of capital are correlated causally with the three basic forms of the individual welfare (figure 2): 248 Emil Dinga / Procedia Economics and Finance 8 ( 2014 ) 246 – 253 Fig. 2. Relations of causality between the types of capital and the components of the individual welfare The social capital originates (primary roots) in the social networks of any kind. These networks can be formal (such as the set of formal institutions), or informal (such as the cultural traditions or the moral principles). In order to formulate a definition of the social capital we need to identify and systematize the predicates of sufficiency of the concept of social capital. We think that these predicates are the following: (PS1): internal pro-cyclicity: the social capital generates a permanent positive feed-back regarding its utilization (stating this predicate is equivalent with stating a “law” of the increasing outputs); (PS2): horizontal non-rivalry: the social capital can be used by any contemporary without reducing, by this utilization, the amount of social capital available for the other contemporaries; (PS3): vertical non-rivalry: the social capital can be used by any non-contemporary without reducing, by this utilization, the amount of social capital available for the other non-contemporaries; (PS4): formal institutionality: the social capital is generated and used only in a formal (encoded)manner. Once an existing entity (having thus objective or subjective ontological status) verifies, simultaneously the four predicates of sufficiency, that entity becomes a species of social capital. Once an existing entity becomes social capital, it generates a new predicate of necessity†: (PN1): axiological assignation: the social capital generates necessarily a list of values which form its reason. Figure 3 shows the general design by which the predicates of sufficiency and the new predicate of necessity of thesocial capital are correlated with the types of capital mentioned earlier: PS1 PS2 PS3 PS4 PN1 Natural capital(CN) Physiccapital(CF) Biologiccapital(CB) Intellectualcapital(CI) Moral capital(CM) Social capital(CS) †The predicates of sufficiency are, logically, predicates of necessity too, but not any predicate of necessity is a predicate of sufficiency too. 249 Emil Dinga / Procedia Economics and Finance 8 ( 2014 ) 246 – 253 Fig. 3.Association of the predicates of sufficiency and necessity with the generic types of capital 1.3. What types of social capital exist? In order to identify the typology of the social capital we need, of course, a criterion (or a set of criteria) of classification. In our opinion, we must use two categories of criteria: (a) (IS): criterion of socialisation: by socialization we understand the process of insertion of the individual within the society (i.e. establishment of the society through the individual people); (b) (SI): criterion of individualization: by individualization we understand the process of autonomizationof the individual person in relation with the society (i.e. establishment of the individual person by the society). Each of the two categories generates a distinct classification of the social capital: (a) On the basis of the criterion of socialization (IS)we have: Communication (C): extent and quality to which the people can communicate, live and act with and in relation with other people; this type ofsocial capital is „accountable” particularly for the process of communitization (establishment of social communities such as: family, team, club, nation, region, social networks etc.); Participation (P): extent and quality to which the people have the possibility to take part in the public decision-making; is type of social capital is „accountable” particularly for the establishment of the political structure of the society; Mutualization (M): extent and quality to which common purposes and common means can be established by inter-individual harmonization (either cooperation, or competition); is type of social capital is „accountable” for the contractual association of the people (within the nations or states, too). (b) On the basis of the criterion of individualization (SI) we have: Liberty (L): extent to which the people can use their own free-will; Trust (I): extent to whicheach individual person is free to delegate own rights or interests toward another individual person (towards the state or a supra-state, included); Symmetry (S): extent to whicheach individual person has the same access as any other individual person to the societal, public or private, anthropic or natural (education, justice, neighbourhood, opportunity). The types of social capital socialization relate to the nature of the process, while the types of social capital individualization relate to the nature of the phenomenon. This observation might lead us to an interesting conclusion: the individualization of the social capital is the result of the social capital socialization. Therefore, we need to accept a form of apriorism of thesocial capital socialization in relation with its individualization. In other words, we may consider the individualization of the social capital as a specification (in the Kantian meaning of the concept of specification) of its socialization. We consider that the proposals of the dedicated literature regarding the typology of the social capital can be included in the six classes mentioned above. We will now form three pairs of social capital classes, the first component of the pair belonging to the category of socialization, while the second component belonging to the category ofindividualization: Communication-liberty (C-L): we will name this pair as the „axiological binomial” of the social capital; Participation-trust (P-I): we will name this pair as thepolitic binomial” of the social capital; Mutualization-symmetry (M-S): we will name this pair as thepraxeological binomial” of the social capital. The reason for the formation of these three pairs resides in the relation of causality between the components of each pair, so that the arrow of causality originates in the socialization component of the pair and ends in the individualization component of the particular pair (figure4). 250 Emil Dinga / Procedia Economics and Finance 8 ( 2014 ) 246 – 253 Fig. 4.Pairingof sufficiency and of necessity predicates of the social capital to the generic types of capital 2. Concept of social justice 2.1. Social justice – mission of the society (state) Society – understood as objectivities of the social contract between the state and the citizens – has four fundamental missions to accomplish: Ensure the efficient utilization of the resources of any kind, of the human resources mainly(we notice here, therefore, the labour force employment); this implies an asymptomatic movement towards the Pareto- optimal welfare – as it is known, because of the existence of public goods, the Pareto-optimum can be achieved (or approximated) only by the state (government); Achieve social justice: the final distribution of the social results of any kind (positiveor negative) on the basis of fairness; fairness means: a) achieve the primary distribution according to the merit; b) achieve redistribution according to the non-imputable non-merit; Achieve the individual welfare: institutional implementation of a grid of principles which produce and reproduce the social capital (of six types, as mentioned earlier); this mission is transversal (synchronic), functioning intra-generationally; Achieve the sustainability of the societal dynamics: all societal inputs must be „recovered” bysocietaloutputs, sooner or later, in the necessary amount, quality, structure and dynamics; this is a longitudinal (diachronic) mission, functioning inter-generationally. Therefore, all these four missions of the society are linked, directly or indirectly, either to the capital as such, or to the social capital, explicitly. We will now show the causal relation between the second mission of the society (achievement of social justice) and the social capital. 2.2. Merit and non-merit in the human society Merit( ) is anintegrator concept used for the primary distribution of the results of the society’s activity between the individual people (primary components of the society). We were saying in the beginning that the merit is assigned exclusively to the people, not to the groups or classes of individuals, irrespective of the criterion of aggregation. By merit we will understand an intrinsic distributional signaller of a right for the three distinct entities: objects (for instance, actual properties), symbols (for instance, currency of financial bonds) and prerogatives (for instance, roles). The category of merit is indivisible, although its level or form of manifestation can be different. Following are some considerations necessary for the subsequent reasoning. 251 Emil Dinga / Procedia Economics and Finance 8 ( 2014 ) 246 – 253 (1) Merit doesn’t exist as such, meaning that it cannot be claimed/assumed or proved/rejected in itself; it exists only if and to the extent to which it manifests, objectivities within an action recorded by the social environment;by action we understand any exteriorization (perceived by the social environment) of an intentionality, irrespective of the form taken by this exteriorization; (2) Only the objectivation of the merit associates to itpositive or negative significances for the society at the moment when it objectivates (we can notice here a historic character of the merit): if the significance of objectivizing the meritby action is positive (appreciated positively by the society), then the merit signals a level of compulsory primary distribution from the society (social reward), while if that significance is negative, it signals an inverse, compulsory distribution, from the individual towards the society (social sanction). Non-merit ( )must not be confused with the negative evaluation of merit objectivation. Non-meritis, simply the lack of merit.Because, as we have shown previously, merit doesn’t exist by itself, only by its objectivation, non- merit also doesn’t exist in itself, only by the absence of its objectivation. Non-merit is of two types: (1) Imputablenon-merit ( ): is the case when the individual refuses to prove the existence of the merit (this proof comes, of course, exclusively by the objectivation of the potential merit through an action with social significance); as claimed by Kant, failing to make use of a merit (for instance, a talent) isimmoralthe reason why the objectivation of the merit doesn’t occur, is irrelevant; (2) Non-imputablenon-merit ( ): is the case when the individual is in a situation of incapacity to objectivates his/her merit (for instance, the people with various disabilities); we presume that society has adequate criteria and procedures by which it distinguishes non-equivocally between the refusal to objectivate a merit and faking this refusal by mimicking the incapacity to objectivates this merit. 2.3. Distributional principles and criteria The distributional principle is a principle which establishes the distribution of the societal result. In our opinion, the distribution of the societal result has two components: a) a distributive component (D1); b) a redistributive component (D2). Consequently, we need two distributional principles: a) a primary distributional principle (PD1); b) a secondary distributional principle (PD2). The primary distributional principle refers to the direct distribution (the distributive component), while the secondary distributional principlerefers to the indirect distribution (the redistributive component). Both the direct distribution and the indirect distribution also require distributional criteria. We consider that the distributional criterion for the direct distribution must be the merit, while the distributional criterion for the indirect distribution must be the non-imputable non-merit. We have here two difficult problems which we will approach briefly: it is about the two distributions which we may name, a) distribution according to the transferred merit; b) distribution according to the presumed merit. Both for the transferred merit, and for the presumed merit, we give up the issue of merit objectivation. The transferred merit works as distributional criterion, such as merit succession. Merit successions can be legal (stipulated as norms, encoded or informal – such as the real inheritances), or can be voluntary (decided by the individual person). Merit successions can be inter-generational (for instance, a legacy) or intra-generational (for instance, a donation, gift, sponsorship). Merit successions refer to all three categories of merit: regarding objects, regarding symbols and regarding roles. The presumed merit works as a merit generation-type distributional criterion. This is the case of assigning positions, roles, etc. to people who didn’t yet prove, by objectivation, their merit, but who are expected to objectivate their merit by the distribution according to the presumed merit‡. Thenon-imputablenon-merit refers to demonstrable impossibilities to objectivate a merit. These impossibilities can be of two categories: a) endogenous impossibilities (such as a physic or mental disability); b) exogenous impossibilities (such as an obstacle which is out of the control of the particular person – force majeure, for instance). Of course, nobody can claim having non-imputable non-merit if a legal norm prevents the action which would have ‡For instance, we must include here the concept of efficient wage from the economic theory of the labour market. 252 Emil Dinga / Procedia Economics and Finance 8 ( 2014 ) 246 – 253 objectivate the presumptive merit. 2.4. Conditions for the accomplishment of social justice The accomplishment of social justice implies the accomplishment of the distributional objective. As shown above, the distribution of the societal result is done in two steps: 1) direct distribution (primary distribution); 2) indirect distribution (secondary distribution, or redistribution). Question is, does the accomplishment of the social justice imply the accomplishment of the distributional result (primary distribution according to the merit, or the secondary distribution according to the non-imputable non-merit), or does it imply just ensuring the procedural conditions for the accomplishment of the distributional result? We consider that the accomplishment of the social justice implies just the provision of the means to accomplish the distributional result. This means that the normative grid of the society regarding the distribution of the societal result must include all the conditions of sufficiency so that the distribution (according to the two forms) is guaranteed according to the mentioned distributional criteria. 3. Correlation between the procedural distribution and the social capital The objectivation of the procedural distribution, the achievement of the normative (encoded) conditions of sufficiency of the primary and secondary distribution according to the associated distributional criteria, will lead to the causal, structural and functional correlation between the social capital and the distribution of the societal outcome. The following theses can be supported in this matter: a. Social justiceis objectivated within the primary (direct) distribution, within the conditions in which the distribution of the societal output (NB: not just the economic societal output, but any output generated by the society) is done according to the merit. In this case, the type ofsocial capital „served” by primary distribution belongs to classIS, i.e.:mutualisation. b. Social rightnessis objectivatedwithin the secondary (indirect), within the conditions in which the distribution of the societal outputis done according to thenon-imputable non-merit. In this case, the type of social capital „served” by primary distribution belongs to class SI i.e.: symmetry. c. While the social justicedistributes the due and non-merit-based societal output, social rightness distributes the non-due and merit-based societal output. d. While social justice relies on the human condition, social rightness relies on the human nature. Figures 6 and 7 illustrate the four theses mentioned above. Fig. 5.Human nature – human condition in relation connection with the relation social progress-individual welfare 253 Emil Dinga / Procedia Economics and Finance 8 ( 2014 ) 246 – 253 Fig. 6.Distribution and redistribution of the societal output: social justice and social rightness References Clark, T., Woodley, R., De Halas, D., 1962.Gas-Graphite Systems, in “Nuclear Graphite”.In: Nightingale, R. (Ed.). Academic Press, New York, pp. 387. Deal, B., Grove, A., 1965.General Relationship for the Thermal Oxidation of Silicon. Journal of Applied Physics 36, 37–70. Deep-Burn Project: Annual Report for 2009, Idaho National Laboratory, Sept. 2009. Fachinger, J., den Exter, M., Grambow, B., Holgerson, S., Landesmann, C., Titov, M., Podruhzina, T., 2004. Behavior of spent HTR fuel elements in aquatic phases of repository host rock formations, 2nd International Topical Meeting on High Temperature Reactor Technology. Beijing, China, paper #B08. Fachinger, J., 2006. Behavior of HTR Fuel Elements in Aquatic Phases of Repository Host Rock Formations.Nuclear Engineering & Design 236, 54. work_dfyjxwawpbdtdfizshqqhczedi ---- Meeting for Justice I_1III sus monkeys, according to Mary Lou Ballweg, cofounder and president of the Endometriosis Association. The original study, which was begun in 1977 and involved 24 rhesus monkeys randomly assigned to a diet containing 5 parts per trillion (ppt) dioxin (low dose), 25 ppt (high dose), or no dioxin over a 4-year period, examined only reproductive and neonatal impact. It was years after the dioxin diet had been discontinued and autopsies implicat- ed severe endometriosis in the deaths of several of the monkeys, a finding that reached Ballweg by word-of-mouth, that the Endometriosis Association stepped in, just in time to prevent the dispersal of the monkey colony to the highest bidders. The association brought in two of its expert advisors, one of whom coauthored the Fundamental and Applied Toxicology study, to perform a daylong laparoscopy examina- tion on the survivors. The scopes were blinded, and the results were astounding," Ballweg says. Meanwhile, the colony is dwindling as more animals die, and the survivors will reach menopause within three years. The Endometriosis Association is mobilizing to fund as many studies as possible in the remaining time, with a particular interest in exploring dioxin-related immunological alterations. "Endometriosis may be more an immunologic disorder with reproduc- tive consequences, rather than the other way around," Ballweg suspects. "The sad fact," says Rier, who is con- ducting immunologic studies, "is that the best time to have done these studies would have been from the time of exposure over the years the disease was developing, so that changes in immune function and dis- ease progression could have been observed side by side. At this point, we can't tell cause from effect-if the immune changes arise from the dioxin exposure or from the disease." Linda Birnbaum, director of the envi- ronmental toxicology division of the EPA's health effects research lab, concurs: "We do know that dioxin alters the immune system of rhesus monkeys, but 10 years postexposure it's hard to sort out the composite effects. It's highly likely though." Birnbaum adds, "These chemi- cals are associated with an increased risk of endometriosis. This is a very relevant study." Rier's preliminary studies reveal dis- ease-related differences in markers of immune dysfunction such as immune cell cytokine production, increases in tumor necrosis factor, and decreases in inter- leukin-6. Rier is also examining natural killer cell activity and antiphospholipid antibodiles in ongoing studiles. In the randomized rhesus study, as well as in the general rhesus population at the primate center, the spontaneous endo- metriosis rate was about 30%, considerably higher than the apparent rate among women. Even so, the findings in these ani- mals were "minimal," Rier observes, com- pared to the severe and symptomatic mani- festations in 79% of the dioxin-exposed monkeys. Moreover, Rier and others note, the incidence of mild, asymptomatic endometriosis among women is not known. The results of this study have prompt- ed a joint effort by NIEHS, CDC, and Duke University investigators to compare the blood levels of dioxin and related com- pounds in 30 women with and without endometriosis. A larger, more definitive study will be undertaken if higher levels of dioxin are found among endometriosis patients than controls, says George Lucier, chief of the NIEHS Laboratory of Biochemical Risk Analysis. The results of the preliminary study-the first to explore in humans the hitherto unsuspected link between dioxin and endometriosis-are expected by the end of the year. Even if rhesus monkeys are actually more suscepti- ble to endometriosis than are women, "the dose-response relationship and the severity of disease give the rhesus dioxin findings more power," Lucier comments, noting that dioxin's actions both as a potent envi- ronmental hormone and an immunotoxin provide two plausible mechanisms for a role in endometriosis induction. Meeting for Justice An upcoming symposium in the nation's capital will bring together community leaders, government health agency repre- sentatives, and members of academia with the goal of developing research strategies to eliminate environmental health injustice in the United States. Environmental justice indudes issues such as race, socioeconomic class, occupation, differential exposure, and proximity of housing to environmen- tal hazards, all of which may directly affect a person's health. NIEHS, EPA, the Agency for Toxic Substances and Diseases Registry, the National Institute of Occupational Safety and Health, the Department of Energy, and the NIH Office of Minority Research are co-sponsoring a symposium entitled "Health Research and Needs to Ensure Environmental Justice," to be held 10-12 February 1994. Participants will meet for three days in an interactive environment to: * identify at-risk populations and research gaps; * acquire information to develop a com- prehensive, long-term intra- and inter- agency research agenda (with projected funding) that incorporates community needs and priorities of at-risk popula- tions. * design a prevention and intervention model as part of a larger research, edu- cation, training, and community out- reach (multilingual, multicultural, mul- tiracial, and multiethnic) effort; * facilitate public input and participation, especially from underrepresented com- munities, to address problems, design research plans, collect data, and imple- ment plans; * develop mechanisms to diversify the pool of health science professionals to include experts from affected and underrepresented communities trained in environmental health fields as scien- tific advisors and peer review panelists on research studies and health research grants; and * make recommendations on interagency cooperation related to research needs of at-risk populations and target resources that build on strengths of existing agency mandates and directives. "This symposium was planned with the participation of community leaders and concerned citizens working as full part- ners," notes Dan VanderMeer, director of the NIEHS Office of Planning and Evaluation. "We see this as an exciting opportunity to expand and accelerate fed- eral efforts to improve environmental health in urban and rural areas through the involvement of underrepresented persons in development of strategies that recognize community needs." GnomPrjc 572 Environmental Health Perspectives work_dddatdlocnca3prn4cha6i635u ---- OUTLAWING AMNESTY: THE RETURN OF CRIMINAL JUSTICE IN TRANSITIONAL JUSTICE SCHEMES* CRIMINALIZAR A ANISTIA: A JUSTIÇA CRIMINAL NO CONTEXTO DA JUSTIÇA DE TRANSIÇÃO* Abstract: This Article responds to an appa- rent gap in the scholarly literature which fails to merge the fields of human rights law and international criminal law—a step that would resolve the current debate as to whether any amnesty in transitional justi- ce settings is lawful. More specifically, even though both fields are a subset of transitio- nal justice in general, the discipline of in- ternational criminal law still supports the theory of “qualified amnesties” in transi- tional justice schemes, while international human rights law now stands for the pro- position that no amnesty is lawful in tho- se settings. This Article brings attention to this new development through a discussion of the Barrios Altos case. This Article seeks to reveal how an international human rights decision can dramatically impact state prac- tice, thus also contributing to a pending question in international human rights law as to whether such jurisprudence is effecti- ve in increasing human rights protections. The Article concludes by looking at the im- plications of this new legal development in regard to amnesties in order to encourage future research regarding the role of crimi- nal justice in transitional justice schemes. Keywords: Amnesty in the Americas. Tran- sitional Justice. Human Rights Violations. Resumo: Este artigo responde a uma apa- rente lacuna na literatura acadêmica que falha em mesclar os campos do direito cri- minal internacional e dos direitos humanos — um passo que iria resolver o atual debate sobre se a anistia em contextos de justiça de transição é legítima. Mais especificamente, apesar de ambos os campos serem um sub- conjunto da justiça de transição em geral, a disciplina de direito penal internacional ain- da apoia a teoria das “anistias qualificadas” em sistemas de justiça de transição, enquan- to o direito internacional dos direitos hu- manos agora está para a proposição de que a anistia não é legítima nesses contextos. Este artigo chama a atenção para este novo desenvolvimento através de uma discussão do caso Barrios Altos. Este artigo procura re- velar como uma decisão internacional dos direitos humanos pode afetar drasticamen- te a prática do Estado, contribuindo assim para uma questão pendente no direito in- ternacional de direitos humanos que é saber se tal jurisprudência é eficaz para ampliar a proteção dos direitos humanos. O artigo conclui olhando para esta nova evolução ju- rídica a respeito das anistias para incentivar futuras pesquisas sobre o papel da justiça penal em esquemas de justiça de transição. Palavras-chave: Anistia nas Américas. Justiça de Transição. Violações dos Direitos Humanos Lisa J. Laplante ** *This article first appeared in the Virginia Journal of International Law ** Lisa J. Laplante,University of Connecticut School of Law, lisalaplante@hotmail.com 59EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 Lisa J. Laplante 60 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 1 Introduction Until recently, immunity measures like amnesties were considered an accep- table part of promoting transitional justice in countries seeking to address past episodes of systematic violations of human rights. The politically sensitive need to broker peace between oppositional forces often outweighed the moral imperative of seeking to punish those responsible for perpetrating human rights atrocities. The “third wave of democratization” in Latin America during the 1980s con- tributed greatly to this trend, with the use of immunity measures in negotiated transitions becoming an important bargaining chip in brokering political impasse in South and Central America.1 Certainly, the Latin American experience has played a significant role in shaping the debates and direction of transitional justice in several respects. The consistent use of amnesties in the region contributed to the growing acceptance of amnesties in the 1980s.2 By the end of the Cold War, the transitional justice discourse in Latin America centered largely around the truth v. justice debate, which put at issue whether a political transition could or should include crimi- nal trials. Political leaders of these countries often justified the use of amnesty in the name of peace, an argument that went largely unquestioned and resulted in a sort of a political balancing test that more often tipped in favor of assuring political stability over criminal justice in post-conflict or post-authoritarian set- tings. Nevertheless, to assure accountability, these countries often formed truth commissions to conduct investigations and to provide a mechanism for truth telling for the benefit of victim-survivors and society at large. As a result, Latin America helped popularize the truth commission model, reliance upon which grew as a way to compensate for compromised justice schemes. While at first truth commissions were believed to be a “second-best” option,3 they soon beca- me complementary and necessary measures for confronting past repressive and violent regimes through restorative justice. Later, Latin America once again helped reshape the terms of the truth v. justice debate in the 1990s. With national justice largely foreclosed in tran- sitional Latin American countries in the 1980s, many victim-survivors and their advocates resorted to international human rights enforcement bodies like the Inter-American Court of Human Rights (IACtHR) for a remedy. As 1Ruti G. Teitel, Transitional Justice 53 (2000). 2 See Naomi Roht-Arriaza, Truth Commissions and Amnesties in Latin America: The Second Genera- tion, 92 Am. Soc’y Int’l L. Proc. 313, 313–15 (1998) (offering a historical view of the Latin American experience with amnesties and its impact on the general acceptance of these immunity measures). 3 See Diane F. Orentlicher, Settling Accounts: The Duty to Prosecute Human Rights Violations of a Prior Regime, 100 Yale L.J. 2537, 2546 n.32 (1991) (“Whatever salutary effects it can produce, [a truth commission] is no substitute for . . . prosecutions. Indeed, to the extent that such an undertaking purports to replace criminal punishment . . . it diminishes the authority of the legal process . . . .”). But cf. Martha Minow, Between Vengeance and Forgiveness: Facing History After Genocide and Mass Violence 88 (1998) (arguing that truth commissions are not “a second best alternative to prosecutions,” but instead can be a form better suited to meet the many goals pertinent to transitional politics). Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 61EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 a result, international human rights law jurisprudence, frequently discussed by learned jurists, strengthened recognition of individual rights while slowly chipping away at absolute state sovereignty. Although a state’s prerogative to use amnesties dates to antiquity,4 the human rights movement suddenly plan- ted serious questions about such immunity measures legitimacy through three main arguments: first, international law creates a state duty to investigate, prosecute, and punish those responsible for serious violations of human rights; second, international law also provides victims a fundamental right to justice (the “victims rights argument”); and third, post-conflict policy recognizes that criminal justice is good for democracy and the rule of law.5 As a consequence, the truth v. justice question began to tip in favor of criminal trials because the rights of victims now factored into a balancing equation that once only consi- dered the preferences of political leaders and elites. Roughly at the same time as the development of human rights law, a paral- lel development in international criminal law also laid inroads to undermine the validity of amnesties. Specifically, the end of the Cold War permitted renewed at- tention to the use of international and hybrid tribunals for criminal prosecutions, a remedy left largely dormant since the Nuremburg trials in 1945. Jurispruden- ce emanating from these tribunals solidified the principle of individual criminal liability for egregious human rights violations, which previously was thought to trigger only liability based on the theory of the wrongful acts of states. These streams of international human rights law and international cri- minal law together helped cause a paradigmatic shift. Today, amnesties are no longer assumed to be unconditionally lawful within an international legal fra- mework.6 Instead, many scholars now acknowledge that to be legitimate, am- nesties must conform to legal norms. This has created a standard of “qualified amnesties” with customary and treaty law prohibiting bars to prosecution for war crimes, enumerated treaty crimes, and crimes against humanity. Yet, this discourse suggests that it is still possible for nations to resort to amnesties for other serious human rights violations. With regard to this last point, this Article responds to an apparent gap in the scholarly literature which fails to merge the fields of human rights law and international criminal law—a step that would resolve the current debate as to whether any amnesty in transitional justice settings is lawful. More specifically, even though both fields are a subset of transitional justice in general, the discipli- ne of international criminal law still supports the theory of “qualified amnesties” in transitional justice schemes, while international human rights law now stands for the proposition that no amnesty is lawful in those settings. This Article brings 4 Teitel, supra note 1, at 58 (writing that amnesties were granted to nearly all participants in the Athenian Civil War in 403 B.C.). For a general discussion of amnesties, see Gwen K. Young, All the Truth and as Much Justice as Possible, 9 U.C. Davis J. Int’l L. & Pol’y 209 (2003) (presenting a definitional overview of amnesties). 5 Ronald C. Slye, The Legitimacy of Amnesties Under International Law and General Principles of Anglo- American Law: Is a Legitimate Amnesty Possible?, 43 Va. J. Int’l L. 173, 182 (2002). 6 See discussion infra Part II. Lisa J. Laplante 62 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 attention to this new development through a discussion of the Barrios Altos case, a seminal decision issued by the IACtHR in 2001.7 Barrios Altos arose out of a dispute concerning one amnesty law, promulga- ted in 1995 by former Peruvian President Alberto Fujimori, which extended im- munity to all state agents responsible for serious human rights violations during Peru’s internal armed conflict between 1980 and 2000. When Fujimori unexpec- tedly fled the country in 2000, the transitional government sought clarification from the IACtHR on the amnesty laws to determine whether its transitional jus- tice experience could include criminal trials. The result was a prompt decision in which the IACtHR declared immunity measures such as amnesty laws to be contrary to state obligations under international human rights law, a holding that can be interpreted to outlaw all amnesties for acts that constitute human rights crimes. Yet recent scholarship, most notably from the international criminal law field, has ignored this decision or otherwise interpreted it overly narrowly.8 This Article responds by offering a more in-depth understanding of the Barrios Altos de- cision in order to inform the ongoing academic debates on the evolving doctrine on amnesties in transitional justice schemes. In addition, this Article seeks to reveal how an international human rights decision can dramatically impact state practice, thus also contributing to a pending question in international human rights law as to whether such jurisprudence is effective in increasing human rights protections. As a result of the IACtHR ru- ling, the Peruvian Truth and Reconciliation Commission (TRC) fully embraced the principle of criminal justice, seeking to conduct its own investigations to support state efforts to initiate criminal prosecutions. Barrios Altos dramatically altered the Peruvian transitional justice experience, eventually leading to prosecutions of police officers as well as military and civilian leaders, including Fujimori himself. As one of the more recent transitional justice experiences, the Peruvian experience offers an important look at how the concept of criminal justice may now figure as a central component of transitional justice schemes. Additionally, the Barrios Altos decision has also set a new precedent for the region, leading other Latin American countries to annul infamous amnesty laws of the past and finally initiate criminal trials. In light of these recent developments, this Article suggests that the truth v. justice dilem- ma may no longer exist. Instead, criminal justice must be done. To develop this conclusion, Part I of this Article first offers an historical overview of the truth v. justice debate in the field of transitional justice, with a focus on amnesties. In particular, Part I examines the Latin American experience and how it shaped the terms of this debate that eventually pushed criminal justice to the sidelines of transitional justice. Part II discusses how a changing interna- tional legal context helped to contest the use of immunity measures and create the current standard of “qualified amnesties” through international human rights law and international criminal law. Part III then turns to the specific story of Peru in order to offer an historical example of how amnesties create a culture of im- 7 Barrios Altos Case, 2002 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 75 (Mar. 14, 2001). 8 See discussion infra Part V. Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 63EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 punity in national settings characterized by serious human rights violations. Part IV explains how Peru helped to reverse this trend of impunity as well as create a new standard in transitional justice schemes by resorting to the Inter-American System of Human Rights. Part V offers a systematic analysis of the Barrios Altos case in order to demonstrate how it may be interpreted to outlaw all amnesties, a conclusion also supported by subsequent state practice, which is explored in Part VI. The Article concludes by looking at the implications of this new legal develo- pment in regard to amnesties in order to encourage future research regarding the role of criminal justice in transitional justice schemes. 2 Truth v. Justice: the controversy of amnesty within transitional justice schemes This Part offers an historical look at the field of transitional justice. Despite its origins in principles of criminal justice, transitional justice evolved to exclude the use of criminal trials in the decades following World War II due to the wi- despread adoption of immunity measures, such as amnesties, in post-conflict and post-authoritarian countries, especially those in Latin America. This development gave rise to the truth v. justice debate, the evolution and terms of which will be discussed in order to illustrate how international law eventually moved towards bringing criminal justice back into transitional justice schemes. The criminal justice origins of transitional justice run deep. In fact, Ruti Teitel traces the genealogy of transitional justice back to the criminal trials at Nuremburg from 1945 to 1949,9 reminding us that the public imagination and understanding of transitional justice often conjures up images of criminal trials and the punishment of the culprits of displaced regimes.10 Certainly, the prosecu- tions of prominent members of Nazi Germany’s economic, political, and military leadership set a new standard: state actors could be held criminally liable for state crimes.11 Consequently, the Nuremburg trials set an international standard, inspi- ring the trials of perpetrators linked to World War II crimes in other countries.12 Above all else, the Nuremburg trials contributed to the birth of the transitional justice field, to which the general fields of international criminal law and interna- tional human rights law arguably belong.13 9 Ruti G. Teitel, Transitional Justice Genealogy, 16 Harv. Hum. Rts. J. 69, 70 (2003). 10 Teitel, supra note 1, at 27; see also Eric Blumenson, National Amnesties and International Justice, 2 Eyes on the ICC 1, 4 (2005) (concurring by writing that “the duty to bring the worst criminals to justice is a deep sentiment, or an article of faith”). 11 This precept now underscores the subject of international criminal law. See Teitel, supra note 1, at 74. See generally Robert E. Conot, Justice at Nuremberg (1983); Telford Taylor, The Anatomy of the Nuremburg Trials: A Personal Memoir (1992); Theodor Meron, Reflections on the Prosecu- tion of War Crimes by International Tribunals, 100 Am. J. Int’l L. 551 (2006) (providing a detailed history of the history of the Nuremburg trials). 12 Carlos Santiago Nino, Radical Evil on Trial 10 (1996) (naming Italy, Japan, Austria, France, Belgium, Hungary, Poland, and Czechoslovakia as places where additional trials occurred). 13 See Minow, supra note 3, at 27 (1998) (discussing the human rights movement arising out of Nuremburg); Teitel, supra note 1, at 32 (drawing the connection between international criminal law and transitional justice). Lisa J. Laplante 64 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 Although precise definitions of the term “transitional justice” vary, the term ultimately rests on the search for justice in response to past episodes of widespre- ad human rights violations, most often those associated with armed conflict, au- thoritarian regimes, and apartheid.14 In these situations, trials can serve a clearly political purpose by laying the foundation for a transition that disavows the po- litical norms of predecessors and works “to construct a new legal order.”15 In this sense, trials can draw a “thick line” between the past and present to prevent new cycles of violence and to help assure the future of a new democracy.16 History, ho- wever, has shown time and again the difficulties countries face in trying to “close the books” on a past marred by widespread human rights violations in order to build a new legal and political order.17 Partly as a result of these problems, the initial enthusiasm for criminal justice generated by Nuremburg was short lived. Geopolitical changes that coincided with Nuremburg, namely the Cold War, made international trials less politically feasi- ble and thereby also contributed to the decline of international criminal justice.18 A Westphalian philosophy promoted a policy of noninterference that deferred to national sovereigns to decide the most appropriate means of achieving peace.19 Ac- cordingly, despite the millions of people victimized by brutal regimes since World War II, criminal prosecutions for such oppression in that period have been rare.20 2.1 Amnesty in the americas The third wave of democratization in Latin America during the 1980s con- tributed to the international tendency to accept that criminal justice could be compromised during delicate political transformations.21 With the exception of 14 See Louis Bickford, Transitional Justice, in Encyclopedia of Genocide and Crimes Against Hu- manity 1045, 1045–46 (Dinah L. Shelton ed., 2005); Ruti Teitel, Transitional Jurisprudence: The Role of Law in Political Transformation, 106 Yale L.J. 2009, 2013 (1997) (noting the qualitative transition refers to a “bounded period, spanning two regimes”). 15 Teitel, supra note 1, at 30. 16 Juan E. Méndez, In Defense of Transitional Justice, in Transitional Justice and the Rule of Law in New Democracies 1, 7 (A. James McAdams ed., 1997). 17 See generally Jon Elster, Closing the Books: Transitional Justice in Historical Perspective (2004). 18 For example, the regime changes in Southern Europe (Spain, Portugal, and Greece) follow- ing World War II took on a wholly local dimension and further undermined any assumption that criminal justice would be pursued. See Nino, supra note 12, at 16. See generally Anne-Marie Slaughter, Security, Solidarity, and Sovereignty: The Grand Themes of UN Reform, 99 Am. J. Int’l L. 619, 629 (2005) (providing an overview of the concept of sovereignty). 19 See Ian Brownlie, Principles of Public International Law 75–76 (6th ed. 1998) (discussing the principle of sovereignty in international law). See generally Stéphane Beaulac, The Westphalian Legal Orthodoxy—Myth or Reality?, 2 J. Hist. Int’l L. 148 (2000) (discussing the history of the Westphalian doctrine). 20 See John Dugard, Retrospective Justice: International Law and the South African Model, in Transi- tional Justice and the Rule of Law in New Democracies, supra note 16, at 269, 276 (discussing a few of the rare cases of prosecution in Greece, Ethiopia, and Rwanda); Christopher C. Joyner, Redressing Impunity for Human Rights Violations: The Universal Declaration and the Search for Ac- countability, 26 Denv. J. Int’l L. & Pol’y 591, 593–94 (1998) (discussing the rarity of criminal prosecutions since Nuremburg). 21 See Jaime Malamud-Goti, Transitional Governments in the Breach: Why Punish State Criminals?, 12 Hum. Rts. Q. 1, 1–6 (1990). Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 65EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 Bolivia,22 retroactive justice for state crimes in Latin America became uncommon in this period due both to inaction and to the use of amnesties and pardons on a frequent basis.23 Thus, the Latin American experience began to suggest a model of “truth and justice as far as possible.”24 The experience of Argentina, in particular, reveals how practical concerns outweighed principled ones when criminal trials put at risk the complex and de- licate undertaking of political transition. In 1980, the Argentine military dicta- torship agreed to hold national elections conditioned on the passage of amnes- ty laws.25 The subsequently elected president, Raúl Alfonsín, however, created the National Commission on the Disappearance of Persons (CONADEP), which eventually led to criminal prosecutions of top military leaders.26 Alfonsín’s efforts soon backfired when the military showed its dissatisfaction through a series of uprisings. In response, the president passed a series of laws including the Ley de Punto Final (Law of Full Stop), which established an end date to the trials, as well as the Ley de Obediencia Debida (Law of Due Obedience), which provided immu- nity to lower ranked, subordinate officers if they acted within the scope of duty.27 Both laws were perceived as “undercover” amnesties that eventually frustrated national attempts to prosecute perpetrators of human rights crimes.28 Notwithstanding its struggles to assure criminal justice, Argentina establi- shed a new model of transitional justice that looked to other mechanisms for confronting the past and helped make truth commissions an acceptable way to 22 Bolivia stands apart from its neighbors as one of the earliest transitional experiences in Latin America in which criminal trials for human rights abuses were held in a political transition from a military dictatorship. On April 21, 1993, after a seven-year trial, its supreme court convicted former Bolivian military dictator García Meza (1980–81) to thirty years in prison. It also convicted some of his top ministers and paramilitary members. See René Antonio Mayorga, Democracy Dignified and an End to Impunity: Bolivia’s Military Dictatorship on Trial, in Transitional Justice and the Rule of Law in New Democracies, supra note 16, at 61, 61–63. This phase ended eighteen years of military rule (1964–82) due to what René Antonio Mayorga terms the “broad societal demand for justice” coupled with the military’s weak and discredited status. Id. at 71. 23 Nino, supra note 12, at 39. For a discussion of amnesties and basic definitional terms, see generally Roderick O’Brien, Amnesty and International Law, 74 Nordic J. Int’l L. 261 (2005). 24 Andrew Rigby, Justice and Reconciliation: After the Violence 63 (2001) (writing on the Latin American transitional justice experience). 25 The military, led by General Rafael Videla, overthrew civil socialist leader Juan Perón in 1973, but the military’s defeat in the war with Britain over the Malvinas Islands (Falklands) largely discredited them. See Carlos H. Acuña & Catalina Smulovitz, Guarding the Guardians in Argen- tina: Some Lessons About the Risks and Benefits of Empowering the Courts, in Transitional Justice and the Rule of Law in New Democracies, supra note 16, at 93, 101–02 (discussing the Ley de Pacifi- cación Nacional (Law of National Pacification) that granted immunity to armed and police forces for crimes committed in context of the military repression between May 25, 1973, and June 17, 1982); see also Jaime Malamud-Goti, Punishing Human Rights Abuses in Fledgling Democracies: The Case of Argentina, in Impunity and Human Rights in International Law and Practice 160 (Naomi Roht-Arriaza ed., 1995) (discussing Argentina’s amnesty laws). 26 See Acuña & Smulovitz, supra note 25, at 104. 27 Id. at 107–08. 28 See Luis Márquez Urtubey, Non-Applicability of Statutes of Limitation for Crimes Committed in Argentina: Barrios Altos, 11 Sw. J. L. & Trade Am. 109, 112 (2005) (providing a history of Ar- gentina’s amnesty laws). When Carlos S. Menem became president in July 1989, he pardoned top generals and 277 military personnel to attempt to resolve growing internal tensions. Acuña & Smulovitz, supra note 25, at 109–10. Lisa J. Laplante 66 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 fill the gap left by compromised criminal justice.29 By the end of the 1980s, truth commissions in Latin America became as commonplace as the amnesty laws that compelled their conception.30 By the time Chile underwent its transition to civil rule following the end of Augusto Pinochet’s military dictatorship in 1990, victims there also faced se- emingly absolute bars to criminal justice for crimes resulting from his repressive rule.31 At the time, Pinochet still maintained power despite having been voted out of office,32 and the courts remained reluctant to pursue investigations, especially since a sweeping amnesty law passed in 1978 covered all crimes committed by the armed forces from 1973 to 1978.33 Pinochet’s successor, President Patricio Aylwin, instead formed a truth commission to provide a “second-best option” and attempted “to serve a cause—the pursuit of retrospective justice—that is more effectively undertaken by the courts.”34 In doing so, Aylwin essentially adopted the position of “[f]ull disclosure of the truth, and justice to the extent possible.”35 Jorge Correa Sutil points to the continued power of the military to explain why Chile could only secure “a partial truth, a partial justice, and a partial healing of old wounds.”36 Unlike “transition through rupture” or total collapse, Chile’s ex- perience required negotiations with an existing military power base which ultima- tely resulted in pacification laws that limited the ability of politicians and courts to do justice.37 The residual power of former regimes generally helped to assure 29 Truth commissions vary from country to country but are usually official and temporary bodies created to investigate and publish historical accounts of past widespread violations of human rights. See generally Priscilla B. Hayner, Unspeakable Truths: Confronting State Terror and Atrocity (2001) (providing a comprehensive account of truth commissions in over thirty countries since 1970). 30 See Emily W. Schabacker, Reconciliation or Justice and Ashes: Amnesty Commissions and the Duty to Punish Human Rights Offenses, 12 N.Y. Int’l L. Rev. 1, 6–7 (1999). 31 In 1973, Pinochet overthrew socialist president Salvador Allende in a coup. See Naomi Roht- Arriaza & Lauren Gibson, The Developing Jurisprudence on Amnesty, 20 Hum. Rts. Q. 843, 846–49 (1998) (providing a historical account of events leading to Chile’s amnesty laws). 32 For example, even though growing discontent had led to a referendum that voted Pinochet out of office in 1988, the 1980 Constitution allowed him to continue to hold power as commander in chief of the army until 1990. Jorge Correa Sutil, “No Victorious Army Has Ever Been Prosecuted . . .”: The Unsettled Story of Transitional Justice in Chile, in Transitional Justice and the Rule of Law in New Democracies, supra note 16, at 123, 131–33. Pinochet also continued to hold a lifetime Senate seat after being voted out of office. 33 Rebecca Evans, Pinochet in London—Pinochet in Chile: International and Domestic Politics in Hu- man Rights Policy, 28 Hum. Rts. Q. 207, 220–21 (2006) (describing Chile’s amnesty laws); Sutil, supra note 32, at 127. 34 Sutil, supra note 32, at 134–35. 35 Id. at 133 (citing Aylwin’s inaugural speech on March 12, 1990). There were attempts to challenge the amnesty laws based on international law, which were eventually rejected by the Chilean Supreme Court. Id. at 135–36; see also Robert J. Quinn, Will the Rule of Law End? Chal- lenging Grants of Amnesty for the Human Rights Violations of a Prior Regime: Chile’s New Model, 62 Fordham L. Rev. 905, 919–20 (1994) (providing a historical account of the attempts to annul Chile’s amnesty law). 36 Sutil, supra note 32, at 149. The Commission on Truth and Reconciliation was instructed to clarify the truth in a “comprehensive” manner and recommend how to rehabilitate the victims. Working nine months in camera, the commission produced “The Rettig Report” (named after the commission’s chairman Raúl Rettig). See Margaret Popkin & Naomi Roht-Arriaza, Truth as Justice: Investigatory Commissions in Latin America, 20 Law & Soc. Inquiry 79, 84–86 (1995) (de- scribing the work of the Commission on Truth and Reconciliation). 37 Mayorga, supra note 22, at 67. Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 67EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 impunity, especially where there were negotiations relating to their continued pre- sence in local power structures. In these situations, rather than seeking full-scale criminal prosecutions against former regime members, the question became “how much and to what extent justice was possible.” 38 By the 1990s, with amnesty laws established as common fare, the focus turned almost exclusively to truth commissions. Transitions in Central America often mirrored those in South America, resorting to immunity mechanisms to avoid criminal justice and relying almost exclusively on truth commissions to assure that the government provided some type of accountability for past wron- gs.39 The experiences in Latin America began to shape what would eventually be well-recognized as some of the fundamental dilemmas in the growing field of transitional justice and would help define the terms of the truth v. justice debate.40 2.2 Promoting truth commissions over criminal justice Pursuant to the Latin American experience, the “threshold dilemma” of transitional justice became choosing what kind of justice.41 The original strong link of justice to criminal trials spearheaded by Nuremburg was weakened by an “an increased pragmatism in and politicization of the law.”42 This process, howe- ver, was not without resistance. Even when state practice seemed to suggest the futility of any debate, a stronghold of justice advocates remained skeptical that 38 Sutil, supra note 32, at 133. 39 For example, five days after El Salvador’s truth commission published its report in 1993 urg- ing criminal accountability for the human rights violations caused during its twelve-year civil war, the government passed an amnesty law barring criminal investigations and trials. Santiago A. Canton, Amnesty Laws, in Victims Unsilenced: The Inter-American Human Rights System and Transitional Justice in Latin America 167, 169 (Mónica Ávila Paulette & Catherine A. Sunshine eds., Gretta K. Siebentritt trans., 2007). Similarly, the Guatemalan Historical Clari- fication Commission produced its final report, Guatemala: Memoria del Silencio, on February 25, 1999, but was prohibited from naming perpetrators or individualizing responsibility. Joanna R. Quinn & Mark Freeman, Lessons Learned: Practical Lessons Gleaned from Inside the Truth Commis- sions of Guatemala and South Africa, 25 Hum. Rts. Q. 1117, 1122 (2003). See generally Popkin & Roht-Arriaza, supra note 36, at 91–93 (describing the origins of Guatemala’s truth commission). 40 See Bronwyn Anne Leebaw, The Irreconcilable Goals of Transitional Justice, 30 Hum. Rts. Q. 95, 99 (2008). 41 Teitel, supra note 14, at 2014 (discussing the function of law in political transformation). See generally Luc Huyse, Justice After Transition: On the Choices Successor Elites Make in Dealing with the Past, 20 Law & Soc. Inquiry 51 (1995) (positing that transitional regimes face political choices in how to respond to the crimes of their predecessors). 42 Teitel, supra note 9, at 70 (discussing the phases of transitional justice development). Lisa J. Laplante 68 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 realpolitik could once and for all terminate the discussion.43 Their persuasion relied largely on legal arguments.44 Nevertheless, the notion of justice began to take on a broader meaning, pu- shed in large part by a challenge to the binary approach to the matter of accoun- tability that reduced the choice to trials or no trials. As Richard Goldstone, Justice of the Constitutional Court of South Africa, comments: “Certainly there is no one simple solution capable of addressing the complexities and subtleties inherent in a range of different factual situations. The peculiar history, politics, and social struc- ture of a society will always inform the appropriate approach to this question in any given context.”45 Part of this development favoring truth commissions without trials also related to the weakness of national courts in matters of criminal justice because “[c]ourts in newly constituted or reemerging civilian regimes must contend with a legacy of a lack of independence, ties to the old regime, mistrust, fear and corruption, or the inexperience of newly appointed personnel.”46 The perceived impossibility or impracticality of domestic trials led to their elimination altogether. 43 Some reasons for prosecuting include discouraging future offenses, minimizing “self-help” vengeance, promoting reconciliation, respecting the rule of law, and strengthening a new demo- cratic regime. See Alice H. Henkin, Conference Report, in Aspen Inst., State Crimes: Punishment or Pardon? 1, 3–4 (1989). As clearly stated by M. Cherif Bassiouni, “If peace is not intended to be a brief interlude between conflicts, then in order to avoid future conflict, it must encompass what justice is intended to accomplish: prevent, deter, punish, and rehabilitate.” M. Cherif Bassiouni, Searching for Peace and Achieving Justice: The Need for Accountability, Law & Contemp. Probs., Autumn 1996, at 9, 13; see also Charles P. Trumbull IV, Giving Amnesties a Second Chance, 25 Berkeley J. Int’l L. 283, 305–17 (2007) (summarizing the arguments for and against criminal prosecutions). For a fuller discussion of the debates, see generally Miriam J. Aukerman, Extraor- dinary Evil, Ordinary Crime: A Framework for Understanding Transitional Justice, 15 Harv. Hum. Rts. J. 39 (2002) (discussing the justice theories attributed to transitional justice); Richard L. Siegel, Transitional Justice: A Decade of Debate and Experience, 20 Hum. Rts. Q. 433 (1998) (outlining the terms of the truth v. justice debate). 44 Chronologists mark the 1988 Aspen Institute Conference in Colorado entitled “State Crimes: Punishment or Pardon” as the inaugurating event for this debate. See generally Alice H. Henkin, State Crimes: Punishment or Pardon (Conference Report), in 1 Transitional Justice: How Emerging De- mocracies Reckon With Former Regimes 184 (Neil J. Kritz ed., 1995) (presenting a summary of the conference). The debate took on special focus through a scholarly exchange in the Yale Law Journal between Diane Orentlicher and Carlos S. Nino, who served as a legal advisor to Argentina’s President Alfonsín. See Orentlicher, supra note 3, at 2540 (arguing for a duty to prosecute “espe- cially atrocious crimes”); Carlos S. Nino, The Duty to Punish Past Abuses of Human Rights Put into Context: The Case of Argentina, 100 Yale L.J. 2619, 2639–40 (1991) (arguing that political contexts must be taken into account when designing an approach to criminal justice in transitions); Diane F. Orentlicher, A Reply to Professor Nino, 100 Yale L.J. 2641, 2641–42 (1991) (rebutting Nino’s interpretation of her viewpoint on the inflexibility of the positive duty to prosecute). In her au- thoritative first article, Orentlicher sets the legal parameters for a state’s duty to prosecute. Nino, in turn, perceives this as too rigid for the political realities of countries in transition and suggests that we need to be sympathetic to the factual circumstances of each country. Nino also notes that an “unrelenting” duty to prosecute may put leaders under pressure and make them look weak. Nino, supra note 12, at 187. This debate culminated in 1995 with the publication of Neil Kritz’s three-volume book presenting the wide array of opinions on the matter. See generally Transitional Justice: How Emerging Democracies Reckon With Former Regimes, supra. 45 See Richard Goldstone, Preface to Human Rights in Political Transitions: Gettysburg to Bosnia 9, 9 (Carla Hesse & Robert Post eds., 1999). 46 Roht-Arriaza & Gibson, supra note 31, at 844. Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 69EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 For that reason, Chilean human rights lawyer José Zalaquett has argued that “the real question is to adopt, for every specific situation, the measures that are both feasible and most conducive to the purpose of contributing to build or recons- truct a just order.”47 In this stream of discussion, truth commissions were discussed as promoting “a different, possibly better, kind of justice than do criminal convic- tion and punishment—‘restorative’ justice.”48 Soon, transitional justice literature began to examine more fully the validity of alternative justice mechanisms, such as truth commissions.49 The argument was made that these mechanisms provided a better historical account of the past by revealing the patterns, causes, and context of abuses and by challenging the prevailing wisdom regarding former regimes.50 Transitional justice expanded to include questions concerning how to “heal” whole societies, with a restorative focus.51 As Nigel Biggar explains, “[t] hinking of criminal justice primarily in terms not of retribution but of the vindication of victims significantly relaxes the tension between justice and the politics of making peace.”52 His definition of justice folds other kinds of justice (restorative, reparati- ve, historical) into a general category of justice, lessening the urgency of criminal trials. In this way, collecting victim testimonies, awarding reparations, and ensu- ring institutional reforms serve as a proxy for criminal justice.53 Biggar poses the question: “Making peace or doing justice: must we choose?”54 In other words, if all measures count equally toward the same overarching goal of peace and recon- ciliation, then the idea of choice becomes moot. Yet Biggar frames the perceived choice in terms of political demands to make peace and moral claims for justice, overlooking the fact that demands for justice also arise out of legal claims.55 47 See Naomi Roht-Arriaza, The Need for Moral Reconstruction in the Wake of Past Human Rights Violations: An Interview with José Zalaquett, in Human Rights in Political Transitions: Gettysburg to Bosnia, supra note 45, at 195, 197; see also José Zalaquett, Confronting Human Rights Violations Committed by Former Governments: Applicable Principles and Political Constraints, 13 Hamline L. Rev. 623, 628 (1990). The issue of particular historical and political contexts counsels that “true political reconstruction is always a matter of local initiative that does not lend itself to external compulsion . . . .” Carla Hesse & Robert Post, Introduction to Human Rights in Political Transi- tions: Gettysburg to Bosnia, supra note 45, at 13, 19. 48 Kent Greenawalt, Amnesty’s Justice, in Truth v. Justice: The Morality of Truth Commissions 189, 198 (Robert I. Rotberg & Dennis Thompson eds., 2000). 49 See, e.g., Timothy Phillips & Mary Albon, When Prosecution Is Not Possible: Alternative Means of Seeking Accountability for War Crimes, in War Crimes: The Legacy of Nuremberg 244 (Belinda Cooper ed., 1999). 50 See Harvey M. Weinstein & Eric Stover, Introduction: Conflict, Justice and Reclamation, in My Neighbor, My Enemy: Justice and Community in the Aftermath of Mass Atrocity 1, 13–14 (Eric Stover & Harvey M. Weinstein eds., 2004). See generally Lisa J. Laplante, The Peruvian Truth Com- mission’s Historical Memory Project: Empowering Truth-Tellers to Confront Truth Deniers, 6 J. Hum. Rts. 433 (2007) (providing an overview of the justifications for truth-telling exercises like a truth commission). It is noteworthy that while at the Aspen Institute conference there was no agree- ment on the obligation to punish, all participants agreed on the basic obligation to investigate the truth. Henkin, supra note 44, at 186. 51 Teitel, supra note 9, at 77. 52 Nigel Biggar, Making Peace or Doing Justice: Must We Choose?, in Burying the Past: Making Peace and Doing Justice After Civil Conflict 3, 16–17 (Nigel Biggar ed., 2003). 53 See id. at 11–13. 54 Id. at 3. 55 Id. at 13. Lisa J. Laplante 70 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 This period of scholarly debate helped elevate the status of truth commis- sions from a “second-best” alternative to a mechanism at least as important as criminal justice in the transitional justice movement.56 Yet in this phase, the mo- vement often went too far to the other extreme. The celebration of truth commis- sions seemed to overshadow criminal trials, making them seem an almost bygone, antiquated feature of justice.57 Martha Minow, a proponent of the restorative view of justice, described supporters of criminal justice as idealists who espouse “stirring but often shrill and impractical claims, such as the ‘duty to prosecute’” and as scholars who are remote from nations struggling with transitional justice.58 Yet Minow’s account overlooks internal divisions within nations and the fact that local actors, especially victims-survivors, do not easily compromise their demands for criminal justice.59 Indeed, ongoing local challenges to amnesty laws helped keep the embers of the debate slowly burning, ready to explode through an even- tual resurgence of international criminal law. 2.3 Foreshadowing change: south african victim-survivors challenging amnesties Experience on the ground, as documented by anthropologists, has shown that the theoretical debates often overlooked the demands of victim-survivors, whose hunger for trials remained even when elites compromised criminal justice. The events that unfolded around the creation of South Africa’s Truth and Recon- ciliation Commission in 1995 demonstrate this reality.60 The South African expe- rience not only helped make truth commissions a part of popular culture, but also 56 See generally Lisa J. Laplante & Kimberly Theidon, Truth with Consequences: Justice and Repara- tions in Post-Truth Commission Peru, 29 Hum. Rts. Q. 228 (2007) (discussing the heightened status of truth commissions in transitional justice); Charles Villa-Vicencio, A Different Kind of Justice: The South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission, 1 Contemp. Just. Rev. 407 (1999) (discuss- ing favorably the truth commission model used by South Africa); Charles Villa-Vicencio, Why Perpetrators Should Not Always Be Prosecuted: Where the International Criminal Court and Truth Com- missions Meet, 49 Emory L.J. 205, 220 (2000) (advising against an absolute duty to prosecute). 57 See, e.g., Mark J. Osiel, Why Prosecute? Critics of Punishment for Mass Atrocity, 22 Hum. Rts. Q. 118, 119–21 (2000) (providing a summary of the nine arguments against resorting to criminal prosecution following mass atrocities). 58 .Minow, supra note 3, at 28. 59 See Laplante & Theidon, supra note 56, at 241–44 (sharing ethnographic research on the resilient quest for criminal trials). 60 The South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission rose to such a high status that it made discussion of the topic mainstream and spawned perhaps more scholarly analysis than any other truth commission. See, e.g., Kader Asmal, Truth, Reconciliation and Justice: The South African Experience in Perspective, 63 Mod. L. Rev. 1, 10–19 (2000) (discussing South Africa’s Truth Com- mission and amnesty laws); John Dugard, Reconciliation and Justice: The South African Experience, 8 Transnat’l L. & Contemp. Probs. 277 (1998) (offering an overview of South Africa’s amnesty laws and their subsequent legal challenge); Sam Garkawe, The South African Truth and Reconcili- ation Commission: A Suitable Model to Enhance the Role and Rights of the Victims of Gross Violations of Human Rights?, 27 Melb. U. L. Rev. 334 (2003) (discussing the amnesty process from the perspective of victims); Rosemary Nagy, Violence, Amnesty and Transitional Law: “Private” Acts and “Public” Truth in South Africa, 1 Afr. J. Legal Stud. 1, 3 (2004) (arguing that amnesty led to a “truncated” truth). Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 71EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 simultaneously created the inference that amnesties are an acceptable feature of transitional justice.61 Indeed, amnesty in exchange for truth constituted a central aspect of South Africa’s 1995 Promotion of National Unity and Reconciliation Act, promising complete immunity to perpetrators of crimes “associated with a political objective . . . in the course of the conflicts of the past” but only if they offered “a full disclosure of all relevant facts.”62 The law permitted some of the country’s most notorious perpetrators to escape justice and created an outcry, mostly among victims, even while it was applauded internationally as a model for future truth commissions. Eventually this local disagreement led to a legal challenge of the Act ba- sed on both national and international law.63 The South African Constitutional Court, though, dismissed the plaintiff ’s international law arguments.64 It held that, in fact, the National Unity and Reconciliation Act was “compatible” with international law, and pointed to the Latin American experience to validate the use of amnesties in political transitions.65 Although reluctantly concurring in the judgment, in his separate opinion Justice John Didcott explicitly recognized the compromises being asked from South Africa’s citizens in upholding the constitu- tionality of South Africa’s amnesty laws because he conceded that the amnesty laws denied the victims’ their right to justice.66 Significantly, while victim-survivors rejected the decision and lobbied for full criminal justice, the press coverage and public reaction to the decision dismis- sed their concerns due to the hegemonic language of reconciliation.67 Ultimately, the judgment served as a “watershed” in South Africa’s transition as “a reconci- liatory version of human rights talk triumphed” over one that put criminal justice front and center.68 Richard Wilson concludes, however, that “[t]he most damaging 61 See Audrey R. Chapman & Hugo Van der Merwe, Introduction: Assessing the South African Tran- sitional Justice Model, in Truth and Reconciliation in South Africa: Did the TRC Deliver? 1, 8 (Audrey R. Chapman & Hugo Van der Merwe eds., 2008) (commenting that the South African truth commission “captured public attention throughout the world and provided the model for succeeding truth commissions”); Catherine Jenkins, ‘They Have Built a Legal System Without Punishment’: Reflections on the Use of Amnesty in the South African Transition, 64 Transformation: Critical Persp. on S. Afr. 27, 31 (2007) (noting that internationally “the policy of ‘reconcilia- tion’ adopted in South Africa, of which the amnesty process is seen as a part, has commanded considerable respect”). 62 Promotion of National Unity and Reconciliation Act 34 of 1995 s. 20(1), 20(7), available at http://www.doj.gov.za/trc/legal/act9534.htm. 63 The widow of Steven Biko, founder of the Black Consciousness Movement in South Africa and who died from torture in 1977, was the first to bring a case. See Hesse & Post, supra note 47, at 13–14. 64 See Richard A. Wilson, The Politics of Truth and Reconciliation in South Africa: Legitimizing the Post- Apartheid State 167–70 (2001) (providing a historical account of the South African Constitutional Court’s ruling on the country’s amnesty laws). 65 .Id. at 169–70. 66 Id. at 172. 67 Id. at 171. 68 Id. at 172. But see Jonathan Klaaren & Howard Varney, A Second Bite at the Amnesty Cherry? Constitutional and Policy Issues Around Legislation for a Second Amnesty, 117 S. Afr. L.J. 572, 581–92 (2000) (offering a critical analysis of the Court’s decision). Lisa J. Laplante 72 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 outcome of truth commissions is a result of their equating of human rights with reconciliation and amnesty.”69 Wilson speaks of “the large gap” between political reality and the survi- vors’ expectations of justice, since the vast majority of survivors preferred pu- nishment.70 Thus, unlike the passive view of victims presented by Biggar, Wilson introduces us to the idea of victims as protagonists. Transitional justice projects must consider the demands of victims and what they need for closure. These con- siderations put into question the legitimacy of amnesties. Wilson discusses how the ambiguity of international law regarding the le- gitimacy of amnesties at the time of South Africa’s transition made the issue less clear. As Wilson states: “International criminal law is highly ambivalent on the question of amnesty, and the tension between national amnesties and internatio- nal human rights treaties has a long history.”71 Writing in 2001, Wilson points out that this ambiguity allows one, by “quoting selectively,” to “construct an ar- gument to either justify or negate a national amnesty.”72 At that time, the well- -accepted doctrine of sovereign prerogative gave an individual’s right to justice far less weight than the social good of stability.73 With great foresight, Wilson predic- ted that the “stand-off between ‘international retributionists’ and the ‘nationalist pragmatists’ over what international law definitively states on the question of amnesty is likely to shift in coming years,” especially in light of the increasing importance of the International Criminal Court (ICC).74 3 A changing global context: a legal framework to challenge amnesties As the new millennium neared, just as it seemed the truth v. justice debate tipped against criminal justice, the legitimacy of amnesty laws took on “renewed importance” in a new international context.75 Indeed, although successor regi- mes since antiquity have had to deal with the crimes of their predecessors and frequently resorted to amnesties, contemporary developments and globalization began to give this task “an international dimension” through the growth and recognition of both international human rights and international crimes.”76 One sees two parallel movements that now seem to be converging, suggesting that cri- minal justice may once again be a solid pillar in the transitional justice paradigm. 69 Wilson, supra note 64, at 228. 70 Id. at 25. 71 Id. 72 Id. at 169. 73 See id. at 26. 74 Id. at 171. Other scholars and practitioners also speculated that the renewed international commitment to criminal justice would begin to change the terms of the truth v. justice debate. See, e.g., Juan E. Méndez, Accountability for Past Abuses, 19 Hum. Rts. Q. 255, 256 (1997) (“Two or three years from now, analysts will have to reexamine everything said today about truth and justice in light of what these experiments produce.”). 75 William W. Burke-White, Reframing Impunity: Applying Liberal International Law Theory to an Analysis of Amnesty Legislation, 42 Harv. Int’l L.J. 467, 467 (2001). 76 Dugard, supra note 20, at 269. Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 73EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 Today, a more solidified body of international law places new restrictions on local decisionmakers, suggesting that the choice that underscored the truth v. justice di- lemma may be moot.77 Indeed, the transitional justice pendulum has now swung back towards a focus on criminal trials, but this time embedded in legal not moral terms, thereby leaving less room for political considerations and manipulations. Most significantly, with the birth of this new legal union we can glimpse the im- pending demise of amnesty. 3.1 International criminal law: individual accountability for atrocities Clearer legal limits on sovereign prerogatives during political transitions began to form half a century after World War II through the incremental develo- pments of international criminal law. Even though the Nuremburg legacy did not increase the frequency of criminal trials, it did spawn a growing body of treaty law expressly requiring criminal prosecutions.78 Specific international crimes were co- dified in the Genocide Convention,79 the Geneva Conventions of 1949,80 Protocol I and II of 1977,81 and the Convention Against Torture.82 This new international criminal framework was strengthened further upon the creation of the interna- tional tribunals for Rwanda83 and the former Yugoslavia,84 and the establishment 77 See Teitel, supra note 9, at 76. 78 See Kristin Henrard, The Viability of National Amnesties in View of the Increasing Recognition of Individual Criminal Responsibility at International Law, 8 Mich. St. U.-Detroit C.L. J. Int’l L. 595, 600 (1999) (tracing the creation of treaties prohibiting genocide, torture, and war crimes to the Nuremburg principles). 79 Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide, Dec. 9, 1948, S. Exec. Doc. O, 81-1 (1949), 78 U.N.T.S. 277. 80 Geneva Convention for the Amelioration of the Condition of the Wounded and Sick in Armed Forces in the Field, Aug. 12, 1949, 6 U.S.T. 3114, 75 U.N.T.S. 31 [hereinafter First Ge- neva Convention]; Geneva Convention for the Amelioration of the Condition of Wounded, Sick and Shipwrecked Members of Armed Forces at Sea, Aug. 12, 1949, 6 U.S.T. 3217, 75 U.N.T.S. 85 [hereinafter Second Geneva Convention]; Geneva Convention relative to the Treatment of Prisoners of War, Aug. 12, 1949, 6 U.S.T. 3316, 75 U.N.T.S. 135 [hereinafter Third Geneva Convention]; Geneva Convention relative to the Protection of Civilian Persons in Time of War, Aug. 12, 1949, 6 U.S.T. 3516, 75 U.N.T.S. 287 [hereinafter Fourth Geneva Convention]. Cer- tain acts are specified in the Geneva Conventions as “grave breaches.” First Geneva Convention, supra, arts. 49–50; Second Geneva Convention, supra, arts. 50–51; Third Geneva Convention, supra, arts. 129–30; Fourth Geneva Convention, supra, arts. 146–47. Common Article 3 of the Geneva Conventions applies to conflicts of a noninternational nature. See, e.g., First Geneva Convention, supra, art. 3. 81 Protocol Additional to the Geneva Conventions of 12 August 1949, and Relating to the Protec- tion of Victims of International Armed Conflicts (Protocol I), June 8, 1977, 1125 U.N.T.S. 3. This protocol also identifies acts which are classified as “grave breaches.” See id. arts. 11, 85, 86. 82 Convention against Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punish- ment, Dec. 10, 1984, S. Treaty Doc. No. 100-20 (1988), 1465 U.N.T.S. 85. 83 See S.C. Res. 955, U.N. Doc. S/RES/955 (Nov. 8, 1994) (establishing an international tribunal for Rwanda). 84 See S.C. Res. 827, U.N. Doc. S/RES/827 (May 25, 1993) (establishing an international tribu- nal for the former Yugoslavia). Lisa J. Laplante 74 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 of the ICC.85 These developments established the legal norm that the most egre- gious international crimes, including genocide, crimes against humanity, and war crimes, require punishment.86 Suddenly, the status of amnesties became suspect once again as scholars and practitioners speculated whether the ICC would respect national legislation that contravened the very essence of its subject matter jurisdiction.87 The idea of immu- nity took a strong hit after the surprise arrest of Pinochet in London in 1998 and the decision by the House of Lords to strip the former head of state of his immunity during extradition proceedings brought by a Spanish judge seeking to try Pinochet for human rights violations.88 This decision also demonstrated that national amnes- ties have no legal effect in non-national, third country prosecutions.89 A growing international grassroots movement then began to challenge the general acquiescence to the “pervasive practice of impunity” that let those guilty of murder to go “literally, scot-free.”90 The situation in Haiti became a quintessen- tial example of amnesty failing to bring peace and deter future violence, further undermining the political rationale for amnesty.91 Policy arguments then arose in 85 On July 17, 1998, delegates to the UN Diplomatic Conference of Plenipotentiaries on the Establishment of an International Criminal Court in Rome voted to adopt what is now called the “Rome Statute.” Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, July 17, 1998, 2187 U.N.T.S. 90 (entered into force July 1, 2002) [hereinafter Rome Statute]; see also United Na- tions Diplomatic Conference of Plenipotentiaries on the Establishment of an International Criminal Court, June 15–July 17, 1998, Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court, U.N. Doc. A/CONF.183/9 (July 17, 1998). 86 Dugard, supra note 60, at 278 (discussing the significance of the international tribunals cre- ated in the 1990s). 87 Sang Wook Daniel Han, The International Criminal Court and National Amnesty, 12 Auckland U. L. Rev. 97, 97–98 (2006) (exploring the parameters of how the ICC would decide on do- mestic amnesties); Dwight G. Newman, The Rome Statute, Some Reservations Concerning Amnesties, and a Distributive Problem, 20 Am. U. Int’l L. Rev. 293, 296–99 (2004) (reviewing the debates over whether the ICC will respect national amnesties); Darryl Robinson, Serving the Interests of Justice: Amnesties, Truth Commissions and the International Criminal Court, 14 Eur. J. Int’l L. 481, 483 (2003); Michael P. Scharf, The Amnesty Exception to the Jurisdiction of the International Criminal Court, 32 Cornell Int’l L.J. 507, 522–27 (1999) (arguing that the ICC should respect national amnesty laws in some situations); Trumbull, supra note 43, at 286 (concluding that even if do- mestic amnesties have no binding effect on a third party’s ability to prosecute under the theory of universal jurisdiction, political reasons may cause one to defer to immunity measures). The status of domestic immunity measures also arose before the international tribunal of the former Yugoslavia. See O’Brien, supra note 23, at 265–66. 88 Evans, supra note 33, at 209–11 (discussing the history of the extradition proceedings against Pinochet); Andreas O’Shea, Pinochet and Beyond: The International Implications of Amnesty, 16 S. Afr. J. Hum. Rts. 642, 643 (2000) (discussing the extradition proceedings against Pinochet and their implications for the legality of national amnesties and universal jurisdiction). 89 O’Shea, supra note 88, at 643. 90 Joyner, supra note 20, at 595; see also Jenkins, supra note 61, at 29 (discussing the “battle against impunity” that occurred with the status of amnesty in flux). 91 Haiti has experienced continuing cycles of violence and repression in the period since the twenty-nine year “Duvalier Dynasty” (referring to dictator Francois Duvalier, who fled to exile in 1986), due in part to its failure “to expose, let alone punish, the crimes of the past.” Kenneth Roth, Human Rights in the Haitian Transition to Democracy, in Human Rights in Political Transi- tions: Gettysburg to Bosnia, supra note 45, at 93, 95–97. Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 75EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 favor of criminal justice.92 The idea of choice became viewed by top scholars as fallacious given that “the attainment of peace is not necessarily to the exclusion of justice, because justice is frequently necessary to attain peace.”93 Juan Méndez, now president of the International Center for Transitional Justice, wrote in 1997 that transitional governments face “one of the hardest choices” given the tempta- tion to equate reconciliation with “forgive-and-forget policy.”94 Nevertheless, he argued that wounds cannot be swept under the rug and warned against “tokenism and a false morality that only thinly disguises the perpetuation of impunity.”95 The mantra of the movement was reflected in the preamble of the ICC’s Rome Statute, which called for “an end to impunity.”96 The creation of the ICC has been credited by some with ushering in a “new order of international crimi- nal responsibility” to address gross abuses of human rights and fill in the gaps of domestic legal systems.97 Trials suddenly became “an essential component of reconciliation”98 and amnesties were the tools for perpetrating impunity rather than reconciling warring parties.99 3.2 Human rights law: the right to justice and the duty to prosecute One of the other significant challenges to amnesty arises out of the legal framework of international human rights law and the resulting “rights talk” which has made human rights dictum a global norm.100 What was once a matter of only national politics and morality now must be grappled with in universal legal terms. It is important to remember that the political transitions in Latin America occurred before a strong and cohesive international legal human rights framework existed, and thus the choice of approaches was presented in terms of “justice v. democracy”- —a logic of peace and war that omitted almost entirely a “logic of law.”101 The terms of the debate were thus limited to a false dichotomy based on a limited perception 92 “Redressing the wrongs committed through human rights violations is not only a legal obli- gation and a moral imperative imposed on governments. It also makes good political sense in the transition from dictatorship to democracy. In fact, the pursuit of retrospective justice is an urgent task of democratization, as it highlights the fundamental character of the new order to be established, an order based on the rule of law and on respect for the dignity and worth of each human person.” Méndez, supra note 16, at 1. 93 Bassiouni, supra note 43, at 12; see also Dugard, supra note 20, at 285 (“Restoration of fidelity to the law is essential in a society which has been subjected to inhumanity in the name of the law.”). 94 Méndez, supra note 16, at 1. 95 Id. 96 Rome Statute, supra note 85, pmbl. 97 See Newman, supra note 87, at 316. 98 Dugard, supra note 20, at 287. 99 Garth Meintjes & Juan E. Méndez, Reconciling Amnesties with Universal Jurisdiction, 2 Int’l L.F. 76, 76–77 (2000). William Schabas contends that the experience of Sierra Leone suggests that combatants do not necessarily need an amnesty to come forward, and some rebels will never be enticed to testify even with the promise of amnesty. William A. Schabas, Amnesty, the Sierra Leone Truth and Reconciliation Commission and the Special Court for Sierra Leone, 11 U.C. Davis J. Int’l L. & Pol’y 145, 152–53 (2004). 100 See Jennifer L. Balint, The Place of Law in Addressing Internal Regime Conflicts, Law & Contemp. Probs., Autumn 1996, at 103, 104–05. 101 See Méndez, supra note 16, at 7–8. Lisa J. Laplante 76 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 of reality. As Teitel states: “The observation that amnesty practices are often de fac- to associated with transitions is somehow turned into a normative statement about the relation of exercises of mercy to the liberal rule of law.”102 In other words, because amnesty was what most national politicians opted for, it was assumed this was the only acceptable way to establish peace and the rule of law after years of lawlessness and widespread human rights abuses. State practice seemed to demonstrate that amnesties were not prohibited by interna- tional law.103 Méndez recognizes, however, that until recently, many of these po- liticians could not count on “a stronger voice of support from the international community for the efforts [to prosecute].”104 Because human rights treaties are generally silent on the duty to guarantee criminal prosecutions,105 they were once assumed to trigger state liability only where a state failed to protect the rights of individuals under its jurisdictional control. Liabili- ty, in turn, usually led to a declaratory judgment and sometimes to compensation and orders for reform.106 As the truth v. justice debate began to take hold, however, human rights law evolved to include criminal prosecutions. One can see this influence, in par- ticular, in the Inter-American System of Human Rights and its role in expanding in- ternational human rights obligations.107 The Inter-American System traces it origins to the 1948 creation of the Organization of American States (OAS), an international organization comprised of member states from North, Central, and South Ameri- ca.108 In 1959, the OAS established the IACHR to monitor and report on the human rights situations in member countries.109 Ten years later, in 1969, the OAS created the American Convention on Human Rights.110 When the American Convention entered into force in 1978, the IACtHR became the enforcement body for the treaty, with 102 Teitel, supra note 1, at 55. 103 Michael P. Scharf, From the eXile Files: An Essay on Trading Justice for Peace, 63 Wash. & Lee L. Rev. 339, 342–44 (2006) (arguing that state practice does not support the ban on amnesties). 104 Méndez, supra note 74, at 272. 105 Michael Scharf, The Letter of the Law: The Scope of the International Legal Obligation to Prosecute Human Rights Crimes, Law & Contemp. Probs., Autumn 1996, at 41, 48. 106 See Lisa J. Laplante, Bringing Effective Remedies Home: The Inter-American Human Rights System, Reparations, and the Duty of Prevention, 22 Neth. Q. Hum. Rts. 347, 350 (2004). 107 For a more detailed account of the Inter-American System of Human Rights, see Jo M. Pasqua- lucci, The Practice and Procedure of the Inter-American Court of Human Rights 2–7 (2003); Jo M. Pasqualucci, The Whole Truth and Nothing but the Truth: Truth Commissions, Impunity and the Inter- American Human Rights System, 12 B.U. Int’l L.J. 321, 361–64 (1994); Brian D. Tittemore, Ending Impunity in the Americas: The Role of the Inter-American Human Rights System in Advancing Accountabil- ity for Serious Crimes Under International Law, 12 Sw. J. L. & Trade Am. 429 (2006). 108 For a discussion of the historical evolution of the Inter-American System, see Thomas Buergen- thal, Protecting Human Rights in the Americas: Cases and Materials 37–44 (4th ed. 1995); Tom Farer, The Rise of the Inter-American Human Rights Regime: No Longer a Unicorn, Not Yet an Ox, in The Inter-American System of Human Rights 31 (David J. Harris & Stephen Livingstone eds., 1998). 109 Statute of the Inter-American Commission on Human Rights, O.A.S. G.A. Res. 447, Inter- Am C.H.R., 9th Sess., OAS/Ser.L/V/I.4, rev. 8 (Oct. 1979), available at http://www.cidh.oas.org/ Basicos/English/Basic17.Statute%20of%20the%20Commission.htm 110 Organization of American States, American Convention on Human Rights, Nov. 22, 1969, O.A.S.T.S. No. 36, 1144 U.N.T.S. 123. Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 77EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 contentious jurisdiction to issue binding decisions involving human rights violations by member states.111 Significantly, the development of the Inter-American System coincided with the political transitions in Latin America discussed above in Part I. The Inter- -American System generally took a hard stand against prior oppressive regimes. In the mid-1980s, however, the IACHR displayed caution regarding the obligations of “recent democracies” to investigate and initiate prosecutions of human rights violations of previous governments, stating that an international body could only make “minimal” contributions to the “sensitive and extremely delicate issue” of whether recent democracies should prosecute past abuses.112 Undoubtedly, the IACHR’s hesitation reflected the relative youth of the human rights system and the lack of a solidified legal framework to support a more definitive position on the duty to investigate and prosecute human rights crimes.113 However, the IA- CHR began to take a consistent position on the duty to prosecute once the IAC- tHR issued a landmark decision on the matter in the Velásquez Rodríguez case in 1988.114 There, the IACtHR held that state parties have a duty to “ensure” the enumerated rights of the Convention, which, in turn implies the duty of the States Parties to organize the governmental apparatus and, in general, all the structures through which public power is exercised, so that they are capable of juridically ensuring the free and full enjoyment of human rights. As a consequence of this obligation, the States must prevent, investigate and punish any violation of the rights recognized by the Convention and, moreover, if possible attempt to restore the right violated and provide com- pensation as warranted for damages resulting from the violation.115 111 See Victor Rodríquez Rescia & Marc David Seitles, The Development of the Inter-American Hu- man Rights System: A Historical Perspective and a Modern-Day Critique, 16 N.Y.L. Sch. J. Hum. Rts. 593, 608–19 (2000) (providing a historical overview of the development of the IACtHR). 112 Inter-Am. Comm’n on Human Rights [IACHR], Annual Report of the Inter-American Commission on Human Rights 1985–1986, OEA/Ser.L/V/II.68, doc. 8, rev. 1, at ch. V (Sept. 26, 1986), avail- able at http://iachr.org/annualrep/85.86eng/chap.5.htm [hereinafter 1985–1986 Annual Report]. The Commission thus found that the response “must come from the national sectors which are themselves affected, and the urgent need for national reconciliation and social pacification must be reconciled with the ineluctable exigencies of an understanding of the truth and of justice.” Id. 113 See Scharf, supra note 105, at 51 (discussing how the evolution of the human rights normative framework would eventually lead to a change in the IACHR’s position). 114 Velásquez Rodríguez Case, 1988 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 4 (July 29, 1988). 115 Id. ¶ 166 (emphasis added). Several scholars argue that the Velásquez Rodríguez decision should not be read too broadly because the Court did not order criminal prosecutions in that particular case. See Douglass Cassel, Lessons from the Americas: Guidelines for International Response to Amnesties for Atrocities, Law & Contemp. Probs., Autumn 1996, at 197, 210 (questioning if this holding is “iron clad” be- cause the Court did not order criminal investigations in that case); Scharf, supra note 105, at 50–51 (arguing that the Court’s ruling is not an absolute requirement because it did not order criminal investigations at the reparation stage); Trumbull, supra note 43, at 298–99 (adopting the view that the failure to order prosecution diminishes the weight of the case). However, the IACtHR repeatedly refers to this general holding in subsequent cases in which it does order criminal investigations, thus suggesting that the interpretation of these scholars may not be accurate. See Fernando Felipe Basch, The Doctrine of the Inter-American Court of Human Rights Regarding States’ Duty to Punish Human Rights Violations and its Dangers, 23 Am. U. Int’l L. Rev. 195, 196–203 (2007). Lisa J. Laplante 78 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 Thus, if a state fails to investigate, prosecute, and punish perpetrators of human rights violations, it becomes liable.116 Moving forward, the IACHR then consistently began to question the appropriateness of amnesties in Latin Ameri- can political transitions through its reports on individual cases as well as through its annual and country reports.117 The Commission took this position even when countries had created a truth commission, stating that these investigations and payments of compensation were “not enough.”118 In this way, the IACHR became one of the first international human rights monitoring bodies to find amnesty laws contrary to basic human rights princi- ples.119 Yet, because the IACHR’s decisions are not binding, states often respon- ded by either ignoring its recommendation, or providing the classic argument that the need to balance peace with justice justified the laws.120 Nevertheless, these Inter-American System decisions helped build a bridge between the evolving field of international criminal justice and human rights law by recognizing that the principle of individual criminal responsibility is fundamental to the punishment 116 See Naomi Roht-Arriaza, State Responsibility to Investigate and Prosecute Grave Human Rights Viola- tions in International Law, 78 Cal. L. Rev. 449, 513 (1990). The European Court of Human Rights arrived at this same conclusion in Kurt v. Turkey, 1998-III Eur. Ct. H.R. 1152 (1998), in which it held that states have a duty to investigate, prosecute, and punish human rights violations. 117 See, e.g., Garay Hermosilla v. Chile, Case 10.843, Inter-Am. C.H.R., Report No. 36/96, OEA/ Ser.L/V/II.95, doc. 7 rev. ¶ 105 (1996); Consuelo v. Argentina, Cases 10.147, 10.181, 10.240, 10.262, 10.309, 10.311, Inter-Am. C.H.R., Report No. 28/92, OEA/Ser.L/V/II.83, doc. 14 ¶ 50 (1992–93) (concluding that amnesty laws violate the judicial guarantees embodied in Articles 8 and 25 of the American Convention); Mendoza v. Uruguay, Cases 10.029, 10.036, 10.145, 10.305, 10.372, 10.373, 10.374, 10.375, Inter-Am. C.H.R., Report No. 29/92, OEA/Ser.L/V/ II.83, doc. 14 ¶ 54 (1992–93); Massacre Las Hojas v. El Salvador, Case 10.287, Inter-Am. C.H.R., Report No. 26/92, OEA/Ser.L/V/II.83, doc. 14, at 83 (1992–93) (declaring that amnesty laws in El Salvador contravene the American Convention); IACHR, Report on the Situation of Hu- man Rights in Peru, OEA/Ser.L/V/II.83, doc. 31 (Mar. 12, 1993) (“One element that has been par- ticularly disturbing to the Commission is that up until 1990, no member of the security forces had been tried and punished for involvement in human rights violations.”), available at http:// iachr.org/countryrep/Peru93eng/background.htm#f.%20Impunity; 1985–1986 Annual Report, supra note 112, ch. IV, available at http://www.cidh.oas.org/annualrep/85.86eng/chap.4.htm (ad- dressing political transitions in the region and attempting to strike a balance between peace and the state’s obligation to investigate). 118 Garay Hermosilla, Case 10.843, Inter-Am. C.H.R., Report No. 36/96, ¶ 77. 119 See Canton, supra note 39, at 170–71 (viewing the IACHR’s decisions as among the first to reject amnesty laws). But see Robert O. Weiner, Trying to Make Ends Meet: Reconciling the Law and Practice of Human Rights Amnesties, 26 St. Mary’s L.J. 857, 865–70 (1995) (arguing that the IA- CHR did outright condemn amnesties but left open that if they adhered to certain requirements they would be acceptable). The United Nations has also issued strong opinions on blanket amnesties. See, e.g., U.N. Human Rights Comm. [UNHRC], Consideration of Reports Submitted by States Parties Under Article 40 of the Covenant, ¶ 9, U.N. Doc. CCPR/C/79/Add.67 (July 25, 1996) (commenting on Peruvian amnesty law); UNHRC, Consideration of Reports Submitted by States Parties Under Article 40 of the Covenant, ¶ 153, U.N. Doc. CCPR/C/79/Add.46 (Apr. 5, 1995) (stating that Argentina’s blanket amnesty laws are inconsistent with the International Cov- enant of Political and Civil Rights and expressing concern that these laws may create an “atmo- sphere of impunity” and violate victims’ rights to redress); Rodríguez v. Uruguay, Commc’n No. 322/1988, Human Rights Comm., U.N. Doc. CCPR/C/51/D/322/1988 ¶ 12.2 (Aug. 9, 1994) (holding that Uruguay’s amnesty laws impaired the right to an adequate remedy). 120 See Canton, supra note 39, at 177. Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 79EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 of serious human rights crimes.121 Essentially, a human rights violation not only triggered state responsibility, but could also constitute an international crime.122 States cannot be brought to criminal trials for human rights violations, but the individuals who make up the state apparatus can.123 This development directly challenged the unconditional prerogative of the sovereign to decide matters of criminal jurisdiction.124 The choice of amnesty no longer depended solely on in- ternal political considerations and “elite preferences” because legal rules now tied the hands of politicians in regime changes.125 The rights of victim-survivors, such as the “right to truth” and the “right to an effective remedy” (which includes criminal investigations and prosecutions) now factor into the truth v. justice balancing equation.126 Furthermore, the denial of these rights by a state will trigger new violations.127 Thus, it is now understood that the state not only has a duty to pursue criminal prosecutions, but also a duty to uphold a victim’s right to a remedy.128 3.3 Current affairs: qualified amnesties Despite the impressive inroads paved by the converging paths of interna- tional criminal law and international human rights, the resilience of amnesty re- mains. A majority of scholars and practitioners continue to defend the legitimacy 121 See Mirko Bagaric & John Morss, In Search of Coherent Jurisprudence for International Crim- inal Law: Correlating Universal Human Responsibilities with Universal Human Rights, 29 Suffolk Transnat’l L. Rev. 157, 204–06 (2006) (examining the overlap and connection between interna- tional criminal law and human rights). 122 See Lyal S. Sunga, Individual Responsibility in International Law for Serious Human Rights Violations 20, 50 (1992); Henrard, supra note 78, at 605–09 (discussing the concept of indi- vidual criminal responsibility for international crimes). 123 Joyner, supra note 20, at 607–08. 124 See Antonio Cassese, On the Current Trends Towards Criminal Prosecution and Punishment of Breaches of International Humanitarian Law, 9 Eur. J. Int’l L. 2, 11–12 (1998). 125 See David Pion-Berlin, To Prosecute or to Pardon? Human Rights Decisions in the Latin American South- ern Cone, in 1 Transitional Justice: How Emerging Democracies Reckon With Former Regimes, supra note 44, at 82, 82–84, 100; see also Méndez, supra note 16, at 3–8; Pasqualucci, supra note 107, at 345 (referring to the historical deference to national decisions to implement amnesty). 126 See Raquel Aldana-Pindell, An Emerging Universality of Justiciable Victims’ Rights in the Criminal Process to Curtail Impunity for State-Sponsored Crimes, 26 Hum. Rts. Q. 605, 622–27 (2004) (ex- ploring how criminal prosecutions are included as part of the right to remedy enjoyed by victims in the Inter-American System); Pasqualucci, supra note 107, at 349–59 (discussing the legal duty to ensure human rights by providing an “effective remedy” as recognized by the American Convention); Sherrie L. Russell-Brown, Out of the Crooked Timber of Humanity: The Conflict Between South Africa’s Truth and Reconciliation Commission and International Human Rights Norms Regarding “Effective Remedies,” 26 Hastings Int’l & Comp. L. Rev. 227, 231–54 (2003) (providing an over- view of the right to a remedy in international law). 127 See Aldana-Pindell, supra note 126, at 611. See generally Dinah Shelton, Remedies in Inter- national Human Rights Law 113–43 (2d ed. 1999) (discussing the state obligation to repair human rights violations). 128 See Roht-Arriaza, supra note 116, at 474–89. This general line of thinking originated with the Orentlicher-Nino debate. See supra note 44 (discussing the Orentlicher-Nino debate). This view was eventually adopted by the IACtHR. See Villagrán Morales v. Guatemala, 2002 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 77, ¶ 99 (May 26, 2001) (holding that the duty to prosecute is separate from a state’s duty to make reparations). Lisa J. Laplante 80 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 of amnesties, although now in legal terms rather than practical and political ones. One sees this trend in a new line of scholarship seeking to establish guidelines, tests, and parameters for “legitimate” amnesties.129 Thus, an inverse relation be- tween international legal parameters and amnesties has emerged. As the legal rules regarding transitional justice have expanded, the breadth of amnesty provi- sions has been reduced. Consensus now rejects blanket amnesties barring all types of investigations.130 The question is now: “What type of amnesty is acceptable in a given situation?”131 Part of the answer to this remaining question revolves around the paradox of legality in transitional justice settings: the rule of law depends on strictly ob- serving issues of legality while putting on trial those who forsake the rule of law. Prosecutors in criminal trials must struggle to observe restrictions such as nullem crimen sin lege, which protects against ex post facto justice and punishment for acts not criminalized at the time of commission.132 To counter this problem, it is now generally accepted that amnesties cannot be applied where treaties obligate states to prosecute or where customary law may be interpreted to compel pro- secution.133 Amnesties are unlawful for war crimes and treaty crimes, which are explicitly enumerated in the Geneva Conventions, the Genocide Convention, and the Torture Convention. Each of these conventions encapsulates the doctrine of aut dedere aut judicare (extradite or prosecute).134 Recently, a new line of argument 129 See, e.g., Burke-White, supra note 75, at 468 (proposing that liberal international law theory could be used to accommodate the preferences of individuals and social actors in determining the validity of amnesty); Henrard, supra note 78, at 645–48 (discussing qualified amnesties that include selective prosecution); Newman, supra note 87, at 306–16 (exploring the accepted limits of amnesties); Ronald C. Slye, The Cambodian Amnesties: Beneficiaries and the Temporal Reach of Amnesties for Gross Violation of Human Rights, 22 Wis. Int’l L.J. 99, 121 (2004) (suggesting that the decision regarding who should be protected by amnesty and for how long will influence the legitimacy of an amnesty); Slye, supra note 5, at 239–47 (proposing situations when amnesties may be legitimate, including “compromise,” “corrective,” and “accountable” amnesties); Jack Snyder & Leslie Vinjamuri, Trials and Errors: Principle and Pragmatism in Strategies of International Justice, Int’l Security, Winter 2003/04, at 5, 7 (arguing that the “logic of consequences” should shape “strategies of justice”); Trumbull, supra note 43, at 319–26 (proposing a balancing test using the criteria of process, substance, and domestic and international circumstances to deter- mine when amnesties are appropriate). 130 See Slye, supra note 5, at 191 (discussing the limits of blanket amnesties and the need for states to take action to address the past). 131 See Young, supra note 4, at 239 (presenting a legal framework to advise states on the proper scope of amnesty). 132 For a discussion of the concern about ex post facto issues in international criminal law, see Mark R. Von Sternberg, A Comparison of the Yugoslavian and Rwandan War Crimes Tribunals: Universal Jurisdiction and the “Elementary Dictates of Humanity,” 22 Brook J. Int’l L. 111, 131–32 (1996). 133 See Cassel, supra note 115, at 207–21 (outlining the Inter-American System treaty law that specifically requires prosecution); Trumbull, supra note 43, at 287–91 (outlining the treaty and customary law bases for barring amnesty). 134 For a discussion of the doctrine of aut dedere aut judicare and the offenses to which it gener- ally applies, see M. Cherif Bassiouni & Edward M. Wise, Aut Dedere Aut Judicare: The Duty to Extradite or Prosecute in International Law 3 (1995). On the treaty-based grounds for barring amnesty, see Joyner, supra note 20, at 597–607 and Naomi Roht-Arriaza, Sources in International Treaties of an Obligation to Investigate, Prosecute, and Provide Redress, in Impunity and Human Rights in International Law and Practice, supra note 25, at 24, 25–26 (discussing the rationales of aut Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 81EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 includes crimes against humanity among those for which amnesty is unavailable, even though crimes against humanity are not codified in any formal convention but rather are a part of customary international law.135 Crimes that are part of customary international law that also reach the level of jus cogens come with the corresponding obligation to prosecute as an obligation ergo omnes.136 More recent examples of political transitions, even those in Latin America, have begun to demonstrate the new consensus that blanket amnesties are no longer permissible, further evidencing the growing restraint placed on national politics by international law. The direct impact of an emerging legal framework on amnesties is achieved through state practice as “state officials believe that they are under a legal obligation to hold criminals accountable, in some way, for their actions.”137 States have thus begun to draft amnesty laws in compliance with international obliga- tions.138 Although some domestic courts ruled inconsistently on the permissibility of amnesties, those that recognized and incorporated international law tended to rule against their legality.139 Writing in 1998, Naomi Roht-Arriaza and Lauren Gib- son analyzed lower court decisions on amnesty laws in Chile, El Salvador, Guatema- la, Honduras, Peru, South Africa, Argentina, and Hungary and concluded that “the trend has been from broader to more tailored, from sweeping to qualified, from laws with no reference to international law to those which explicitly try to stay within its strictures.”140 They credit this trend to the “growing importance of a discourse about impunity and accountability on an international level.”141 Despite this evident evolution in state practice, a hard and fast contingent continues to advocate that some amnesties should remain in the “toolbox of con- flict resolution” because of their usefulness for peacemaking.142 Notwithstanding the breadth of academic writing to the contrary, one commentator has also obser- ved that amnesties may not be clearly restricted by emerging international legal dedere aut judicare). In 2000, the UN Secretary-General adopted the position that amnesties could not be granted for international crimes such as genocide, crimes against humanity, or other serious violations of international humanitarian law. The Secretary-General, Report of the Secretary-General on the Establishment of a Special Court for Sierra Leone, ¶ 22, delivered to the Security Council, U.N. Doc. S/2000/915 (Oct. 4, 2000); see also The Secretary-General, Report of the Secre- tary-General on the Rule of Law and Transitional Justice in Conflict and Post-Conflict Societies, ¶ 64(c), delivered to the Security Council, U.N. Doc. S/2004/616 (Aug. 23, 2004) (rejecting amnesties for genocide, war crimes, and crimes against humanity). But see Scharf, supra note 105, at 360–63 (arguing that the duty to prosecute is only required by treaty and not by customary law). 135 M. Cherif Bassiouni, “Crimes Against Humanity”: The Need for a Specialized Convention, 31 Colum. J. Transnat’l L. 457, 475 (1994); M. Cherif Bassiouni, International Crimes: Jus Cogens and Obligatio Erga Omnes, Law & Contemp. Probs., Autumn 1996, at 63 (arguing that states have an obligation to prosecute for inderogable rights). 136 See Roht-Arriaza, supra note 116, at 489–505 (discussing the customary law duty to pros- ecute). 137 Trumbull, supra note 43, at 301. 138 See Lynn Berat, South Africa: Negotiating Change?, in Impunity and Human Rights in Interna- tional Law and Practice, supra note 25, at 267, 280 (discussing South Africa’s “rejection of a blanket amnesty and declared intent to abide by international law”). 139 Roht-Arriaza & Gibson, supra note 31, at 870. 140 Id. at 884. 141 Id.; see also Robert E. Lutz, A Piece of Peace: The Human Rights Accord and the Guatemalan Peace Process, 2 Sw. J. L. & Trade Am. 183 (1995). 142 See Schabas, supra note 99, at 165–66. Lisa J. Laplante 82 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 rules: “Despite the growing tension between the development of international criminal laws and institutions on the one hand, and state practice embracing amnesties on the other, there is surprisingly little international law that directly addresses the legitimacy of amnesties.”143 3.4 Calls for clarity: the uncertain future of amnesties in human rights protection Despite recent encroachments upon the validity of amnesties, the status of an outright prohibition on amnesties remains unclear. At question is whether am- nesties may be applied to crimes that constitute serious human rights violations, but do not fall into the category of treaty crimes, war crimes, or crimes against humanity. Some argue that “[w]hile international human rights groups, following human rights interpretations of international criminal law, have been enthusiastic about a complete end to amnesties, there is room for substantial ongoing legal and philosophical analysis of the questions at stake.”144 Since there is no explicit ban on all amnesties at the moment, limits must be judicially prescribed.145 In this vein, Michael Scharf in 1996 pointed out, “Once it is recognized that there is a gap in the international law requiring prosecution, two approaches are possible: one is to exploit the gap, the other is to attempt to fill it.”146 Given the risk of the former, advocates now eagerly wait for an inter- national authority to fill it. Charles Trumbull observes that given the deadlock among scholars, “the legality of amnesties for perpetrators of serious crimes under international law is in a state of transition and considerable uncertainty.”147 He then writes: “The need for the international community to reach consensus on the validity of amnesties has become more acute in light of the controversial am- nesties recently adopted by several countries.”148 4 Peru: legalizing impunity through amnesty Peru represents a new stage in the development of the transitional justice paradigm. In its endeavor to address the past without providing impunity, it has included criminal justice in its transitional process from the beginning. Peru has 143 Slye, supra note 5, at 179. 144 Newman, supra note 87, at 315. 145 See Young, supra note 4, at 232 (“No treaty provisions specifically prohibit amnesty.”). 146 Scharf, supra note 105, at 61. 147 Trumbull, supra note 43, at 285. 148 Id. at 286. There has been an attempt to create “soft law” through a consensus of academ- ics, specifically by the drafting of the Princeton Principles on Universal Jurisdiction in 2001. Princeton Univ. Program in Law & Pub. Affairs, Princeton Principles on Universal Jurisdiction (2001), reprinted in Universal Jurisdiction 21 (Stephen Macedo ed., 2004) [hereinafter Princ- eton Principles on Universal Jurisdiction]. After extensive debate, however, the scholars were not able to agree on a per se rule regarding the legality of amnesty, deciding instead that “[a]mnes- ties are generally inconsistent with the obligation of states to provide accountability for serious crimes under international law.” Trumbull, supra note 43, at 298 (quoting Princeton Principles on Universal Jurisdiction, supra, princ. 7). Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 83EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 set a new trend of state practice by specifically rejecting amnesty laws in its do- mestic political transition, and in doing so has helped resolve the pending ques- tion on the status of amnesties. It is important to contextualize any analysis of Peru’s legal experience by first understanding its story—how it fell into authorita- rianism and finally found its way out. Peru’s unique history has been significan- tly influenced by the Inter-American System of Human Rights, which became a great ally of the local human rights movement prior to the country’s transition. A symbiotic national-international relationship, which continues today, has ensured that, above all else, Peru fulfills its duty to protect and respect the right to justice. This collaboration of sorts began over a decade ago during the height of Fujimori’s authoritarian regime. Local victim-survivors and their advocates made “good use” of the international system to influence and support the formation of the TRC and the criminal trials that soon followed.149 Ultimately, as will be discussed in more detail below, the investigations and consequent rulings of the IACHR and the IACtHR set the terms for Peru’s approach to transitional justice, which fully embraced the principle of criminal justice. 4.1 In the name of national security Perhaps one of the Inter-American System’s greatest contributions to Peru’s national criminal justice experience was its condemnation of Fujimori’s regime through a series of cases submitted throughout the 1990s. These cases reached the Inter-American System because of the wholly ineffective recourse provided by the Peruvian domestic legal system.150 Among these, the Barrios Altos and La Cantuta cases would particularly impact the criminal justice aspect of Peru’s tran- sitional justice experience.151 Both cases revolved around an undercover death squad—a centerpiece of Fujimori’s national security apparatus. Fujimori won the 1990 presidential election as a political unknown.152 Over the following years, with the help of his right hand advisor Vladimir Montesinos, he took carefully calculated steps to gain steadily almost absolute executive po- wer, justifying his newfound authority under the guise of fighting terrorism.153 The previous administration of Alan García (1985–90) left a country devastated by both economic collapse154 and a ten-year internal armed conflict with insur- 149 Lisa J. Laplante, Entwined Paths to Justice: The Inter-American Human Rights System and the Peru- vian Truth Commission, in Paths to International Justice: Social and Legal Perspectives 216, 237 (Marie-Bénédicte Dembour & Tobias Kelly eds., 2007). 150 See id. at 219. 151 Barrios Altos Case, 2002 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 75, ¶ 2(a) (Mar. 14, 2001); La Cantuta Case, 2007 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 162, ¶ 80(18) (Nov. 29, 2006). For further discussion of these cases, see infra Part V. 152 Catherine M. Conaghan, Fujimori’s Peru: Deception in the Public Sphere 15–18 (2005) (giv- ing a historical account of the 1990 Peruvian elections and Fujimori’s candidacy). 153 Sally Bowen & Jane Holligan, El Espía Imperfecto: La Telaraña Siniestra de Vladimiro Mon- tesinos (2003) (offering a full account of the political, often illegal, influence of Montesinos on Fujimori). 154 See Eduardo Ferrero Costa, Peru’s Presidential Coup, 4 J. Democracy 28, 29 (1993) (describing how García’s policies led to spiraling foreign debt, an inflation rate that reached a rate of seven Lisa J. Laplante 84 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 gent groups including the Communist Party of Peru-Shining Path (PCP-SL).155 Fujimori capitalized on the deep unease and fear that saturated Peruvian society as a result of these circumstances by taking drastic measures to promote his free market economic plan and clamp down on political opponents.156 With the sup- port of the armed forces, Fujimori conducted an autogolpe (self-coup) on April 5, 1992, in which he shut down the bicameral Congress, dismantled the judiciary, and suspended the national constitution.157 To assure enforcement of his new authoritarian regime, he hand picked General Nicolás De Bari Hermoza-Ríos to be the Commander General of the Army and Head of the Joint Command158 and gave the executive branch direct control over the Servicio de Inteligencia Nacional (SIN) by appointing Montesinos as its de facto executive chief.159 SIN, in turn, created the death squad called El Grupo Colina (Colina).160 Colina consisted of thirty-two men and six women and worked clandestine- ly in collaboration with the Intelligence Services of the Armed Forces (SIE) under the direction of Army Majors Santiago Martín Rivas and Carlos Eliseo Pichilin- güe-Guevara.161 This clandestine group was formed to carry out “a State policy consisting in the identification, control and elimination of those persons suspec- ted of belonging to insurgent groups or who [were] opposed to the government of former President Alberto Fujimori. It operated through the implementation of systematic indiscriminate extra-legal executions, selective killings, forced disa- thousand percent and a gross national product drop of twelve percent). 155 A few years later, the insurgent group Tupac Amaru Revolutionary Movement joined the internal armed conflict. For more background on Peru’s internal armed conflict, see generally Gustavo Gorriti, The Shining Path: A History of the Millenarian War in Peru (Robin Kirk trans., Univ. N.C. Press 1999) (1990) (offering a journalist’s historical account of the strategy, actions, and challenges of the state and rebels during the war); Orin Starn, Maoism in the Andes: The Communist Party of Peru-Shining Path and the Refusal of History, 27 J. Latin Am. Stud. 399 (1995). 156 See Jo-Marie Burt, “Quien habla es terrorista”: The Political Use of Fear in Fujimori’s Peru, 41 Latin Am. Res. Rev. 32, 47 (2006) [hereinafter Burt, Quien habla]; Jo-Marie Burt, State Making Against Democracy: The Case of Fujimori’s Peru, in Politics in the Andes: Identity, Conflict, Reform 247, 255–57 (Jo-Marie Burt & Philip Mauceri eds., 2004) (describing the reconstitution of authori- tarianism in response to political violence and high inflation in Peru). 157 Maxwell A. Cameron, Latin American Autogolpes: Dangerous Undertows in the Third Wave of Democ- ratization, 19 Third World Q. 219, 224, 228–29 (1998) [hereinafter Cameron, Autogolpes]; Max- well A. Cameron, Self-Coups: Peru, Guatemala, and Russia, 9 J. Democracy 125, 127 (1998) [herein- after Cameron, Self-Coups]. See generally Charles D. Kenney, Fujimori’s Coup and the Breakdown of Democracy in Latin America (2004) (providing a comprehensive analysis of Fujimori’s self-coup). 158 See Cameron, Autogolpes, supra note 157, at 236. 159 General Julio Salazar-Monroe was SIN’s official director. Until this time, the SIN had with- ered under civilian rule and was a small, underfunded organization. Fujimori reinvigorated the office and it grew to employ thousands of agents and became “an indispensable part of the gov- ernment’s political machine and an instrument for isolating, discrediting, and spying on oppo- nents.” Roger Atwood, Democratic Dictators: Authoritarian Politics in Peru from Leguía to Fujimori, 21 SAIS Rev. Int’l Aff. 155, 171 (2001). The power of the intelligence services was also increased by the appointment of Nélida Colán as attorney general. Colán “did little to defend citizens’ rights” in the wake of major abuses by the intelligence services and removed several judges who displayed an independent streak. Cameron, Self-Coups, supra note 157, at 130. 160 See Cameron, Self-Coups, supra note 157, at 127. 161 Efraín Rúa, El Crimen de la Cantuta: La Desaparición y Muerte de un Profesor y Nueve Es- tudiantes que Estremeció al País 119–20, 130 (2005). Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 85EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 ppearances and tortures.”162 Although the leader of Shining Path was captured on September 12, 1992, and the insurgent movement and violence declined, Colina continued to operate under the justification of heightened national security due to alleged terrorism.163 As Peru’s “political police,” the death squad would go on to carry out some of Peru’s most notorious massacres, including those at Barrios Altos and La Cantuta.164 4.2 The massacres of barrios altos and la cantuta Peruvian journalist and author Efraín Rúa describes the Barrios Altos mas- sacre as Colina’s “consecrating act”—one that would be a rite of passage for a small group of army officers who would go on to conduct some of Peru’s most ruthless tragedies.165 This nefarious story began on November 3, 1991, when neighbors of the poor Lima neighborhood of Barrios Altos held a pollada (fundraiser) to help replace faulty drains and piping that were making their children sick.166 Around 11:30 p.m., two vehicles with sirens pulled up to the dwelling and six armed, masked men descended upon the party.167 For the next few minutes, the men fired with silencers on the crowd, killing fifteen people, including an eight-year-old child who had run to his father’s aid pleading for the killers to have mercy.168 Four other people were seriously wounded, including one man who was paralyzed after being hit with twenty-seven bullets.169 Information came forward that the Barrios Altos massacre was conducted by a government affiliated death squad as part of 162 La Cantuta Case, 2007 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 162, ¶ 80(18) (Nov. 29, 2006). The IACtHR also referred to the findings of the Peruvian TRC: “The so-called ‘Colina Group,’ composed of members of the Army, is probably one of the groups specialized in forced disap- pearances and arbitrary executions most widely known . . . . In 1991, top military and political authorities ordered the officers of the intelligence operations division (AIO) belonging to the Servicio de Inteligencia del Ejército (SIE) (Army Intelligence Service) to create a squad reporting to the structure of the Dirección de Inteligencia del Ejército Peruano (DINTE), which was then known as ‘Colina Detachment.’ This group was in charge of operations especially designed to eliminate alleged subversives, sympathizers or collaborators of subversive organizations.” Id. ¶ 80(18) n.25 (quoting 6 Comisión de la Verdad y Reconciliacion [Truth & Reconciliation Com- mission], Informe Final [Final Report] 154 (2003) (Peru), available at http://www.cverdad.org.pe/ ifinal/pdf/TOMO%20VI/SECCION%20CUARTA-Crimenes%20y%20violaciones%20DDHH/ FINAL-AGOSTO/1.3.%20EJECUCIONES%20ARBITRARIAS.pdf ). 163 See Audrey Kurth Cronin, How al-Qaida Ends: The Decline and Demise of Terrorist Groups, Int’l Security, Summer 2006, at 7, 20 (arguing that the capture of Abimael Guzman led to the demise of Shining Path). 164 Burt, Quien habla, supra note 156, at 47–48. Colina was named after José Pablo Colina Gaige, a secret intelligence agent who had infiltrated PCP-SL and was killed in a “friendly fire” incident in 1984 by a state agent who had been ordered not to bring back detainees. Rúa, supra note 161, at 129. 165 Rúa, supra note 161, at 129. 166 Id. at 123. 167 Barrios Altos Case, 2002 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 75, ¶ 2(a) (Mar. 14, 2001). It was eventually revealed that the trucks had belonged to Fujimori’s brother and the Vice-Minister of the Interior who later reported the trucks stolen. Rúa, supra note 161, at 127. 168 Barrios Altos, 2002 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 75, ¶ 2(b); Rúa, supra note 161, at 125. 169 Barrios Altos, 2002 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 75, ¶ 2(b); Rúa, supra note 161, at 125. Lisa J. Laplante 86 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 an anti-terrorism campaign.170 On November 27, 1991, the Peruvian Congress created a committee to investigate the Barrios Altos massacre, but its efforts were thwarted by Fujimori’s self-coup that dissolved Congress in April 1992.171 The issue of justice for Barrios Altos would not be revisited for another three years. The next notorious act attributed to Colina allegedly occurred as revenge for one of Lima’s worst acts of terrorism. On July 16, 1992, one hundred days after Fujimori’s self-coup, two young men pulled a car up to a plaza in the center of the urban town Miraflores, one of the upper class boroughs of Lima. A security guard shot at them as they fled the scene. Seconds later, the trucks they had been driving exploded, destroying the surrounding Tarata apartment building, killing twenty-two people and seriously injuring two hundred more.172 The next day, SIN received information that the fleeing culprits arrived bleeding at La Cantuta, formally known as the Universidad Enrique Guzmán y Valle.173 Already, Peruvian universities suffered great tension because they were suspected of serving as fee- ding ground for new PCP-SL recruits, and as a result military stations had been installed on many school grounds including La Cantuta.174 On the day after the Tarata bombing, Colina members arrived at La Cantuta in the early morning hours, passing with the permission of the soldiers guarding the front entrance.175 They barged into the dorms, pulled sleeping students from their beds, hit and threatened them, took some into the yard, and eventually loa- ded nine of them into their trucks.176 They also took Professor Hugo Muñoz-San- chez from his home in a hood, locking his wife and little boy in the bathroom.177 The nine students and Professor Muñoz-Sanchez were driven to a nearby arid stretch of land in the district of Cieneguilla called the “boca del diablo” (devil’s mouth),178 where they were executed by shots to the back of the head and then 170 Barrios Altos, 2002 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 75, ¶ 2(d). 171 Id. ¶ 2(f). 172 Rúa, supra note 161, at 159. 173 Id. at 163. 174 The government had authorized the entry of the security forces to the universities through Decree-Law No. 726 of November 8, 1991. La Cantuta Case, 2007 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 162, ¶ 80(10) (Nov. 29, 2006). The IACtHR referred to the Peruvian TRC’s account of this situation: “At the beginning of 1991, the local TV released a video of a political-cultural ceremony held at ‘La Cantuta’ University that allowed speculating about the level of control that ‘Sendero Luminoso’ (Shinning Path [sic]) had in the University. On May 21, 1991, former President Alberto Fujimori visited the university causing the violent reaction of students that forced him to leave the campus, humiliated. The following day, military troops took control of the Universidad Mayor de San Marcos and of ‘La Cantuta’ University, and 56 students were ar- rested. Among them there were three of the nine students that were subsequently subjected to extra-legal execution.” Id. (quoting 7 Comisión de la Verdad y Reconciliacion [Truth & Recon- ciliation Commission], supra note 162, at 234, available at http://www.cverdad.org.pe/ifinal/pdf/ TOMO%20VII/Casos%20Ilustrativos-UIE/2.22.%20LA%20CANTUTA.pdf). 175 See La Cantuta, 2007 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 162, ¶ 80(12). 176 The abducted students were: Juan Mariños-Figueroa, Bertila Lozano-Torres, Roberto Teo- doro-Espinoza, Marcelino Rosales-Cárdenas, Felipe Flores-Chipana, Luis Enrique Ortiz-Perea, Armando Amaro-Cóndor, Heráclides Pablo-Meza, and Dora Oyague-Fierro. Id. ¶ 80(15). 177 Rúa, supra note 161, at 18. 178 Id. Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 87EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 buried.179 Some days later, Colina agents returned to burn and rebury the bodies in a new common grave in Huachipa.180 Over the following days and weeks, the families of the nine missing stu- dents and one professor began to learn of the event through friends, family, and newspaper headlines, starting a search for justice that continues today.181 The families visited police stations, military barracks, and local municipalities, all of which denied knowledge of the events at La Cantuta. Antonia Pérez-Velásquez de Muñoz, wife of Hugo Muñoz-Sanchez, said it was as if “he had vanished off the face of the earth.”182 They were not deterred by death threats or the resistance of people who suspected their loved ones of being terrorists.183 The families, as well as the dean of La Cantuta, eventually filed three habeas corpus petitions, all of which were dismissed as groundless. The military, including Luis Salazar-Monroe and General Nicolás de Bari Hermoza-Ríos, denied knowledge of the attack and refused to provide information citing “national security reasons.”184 The families also filed criminal complaints in July and August of 1992.185 On April 2, 1993, while the families unsuccessfully sought a legal remedy, Henry Pease-García, a progressive Peruvian Congressman, received an anonymous document from an army faction calling itself the “León Dormido” (Sleeping Lion) identifying the masterminds of the La Cantuta disappearances.186 A congressional committee was formed to further investigate the case, but it faced considerable obs- tacles, including the military’s refusal to testify. Even when General Hermoza-Ríos eventually appeared before the committee on April 20, 1993, he denied that the army participated in the disappearances and, upon leaving, read a statement to the press accusing the congressional members of working “in collusion with the terrorists” and participating in “the orchestration of a well-thought and planned campaign to impair the prestige and honor of the Peruvian Army.”187 The next day, military tanks circulated throughout the capital city of Lima and stationed near the Congress buil- ding. General Hermoza-Ríos issued more statements regarding the “false” accusations constituting a systematic campaign to undermine the military’s ability to fight terro- rism and forbade any officer from cooperating with the committee.188 In May 1993, Peruvian General Rodolfo Robles Espinoza, Commander General of the Third Military Region, publicly declared that he had reliable in- 179 Id. at 169–74. 180 See La Cantuta, 2007 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 162, ¶¶ 80(16), (31). 181 See id. ¶¶ 60(a)–(g), 61 (providing the testimonies of next of kin). 182 Id. ¶ 61(c). 183 See id. ¶ 60. 184 Id. ¶ 80(20)(ii)–(iii); see also Rúa, supra note 161, at 185–86. 185 La Cantuta, 2007 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 162, ¶ 80(20). Antonia Pérez-Velásquez de Muñoz reported the disappearance of her husband to the Provincial Criminal Prosecutor´s Office of the Tenth Prosecutor´s Office on July 21, 1992. Id. ¶ 80(21). 186 Id. ¶ 80(25). 187 Id. ¶ 80(27); see also Rúa, supra note 161, at 205. 188 This military stand off finally came to a halt through international pressures, and Defense Minister Víctor Malca eventually brought the bravado display to a halt, but by then General Hermoza-Ríos had ordered a freeze on any testimony before the congressional committee. Rúa, supra note 161, at 206–12. Lisa J. Laplante 88 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 formation that Colina was responsible for the La Cantuta murders, an act that forced him to go into exile in Argentina after thirty-seven years of service.189 Soon after, in July 1993, journalists of the local newspaper Sí received a hand-drawn map that claimed to point to the buried bodies of the La Cantuta victims and a note that provided minute details of the clandestine graves.190 This clue led to the discovery of the hidden graves and, under the supervision of prosecutor Victor Cubas-Villanueva, the recovery of burned bones and clothing, all recognized by the next of kin in attendance.191 Keys were also found which opened the dormi- tory locker of one of the murdered students and the front door of another. This breakthrough led Congresswomen Gloria Helfer, who also worked on the special congressional committee, to remark: “The dead are talking, and they are saying the perpetrators are free and they are demanding justice.”192 4.3 The pressure to prosecute and the battle of jurisdiction In the quest to obtain justice through the courts, the families and their allies found the jurisdictional conflict between ordinary civilian criminal courts and military courts to be their greatest obstacle. For example, the Peruvian At- torney General ordered prosecutors to begin investigations into the murders on August 6, 1992.193 The prosecutor’s office declined jurisdiction, however, because the same facts were already being reviewed by the War Chamber of the Supreme Council of Military Justice (SCMJ), a decision eventually affirmed on appeal.194 Other ongoing challenges included reluctant or uncooperative civil judges and the political harassment and replacement of prosecutors.195 The military investigation opened in April 1993, but did not progress until the discovery of the clandestine graves, at which point the SCMJ Investigation Board admitted the complaint filed by the War Chamber Prosecutor.196 Rightly suspecting that the military’s co-option of the criminal investi- gations was a subterfuge to halt justice, the families persisted with their civil claims. On December 15, 1993, they filed criminal complaints against Retired Army Captain Montesinos and Generals Hermoza-Ríos, Luis Pérez-Documet, Ju- 189 La Cantuta, 2007 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 162, ¶ 80(17); Rúa, supra note 161, at 211–12. 190 La Cantuta, 2007 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 162, ¶ 80(30); Rúa, supra note 161, at 228. 191 La Cantuta, 2007 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 162, ¶¶ 80(30)–(31). 192 Rúa, supra note 161, at 238 (author’s translation). 193 La Cantuta, 2007 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 162, ¶ 80(23). 194 Id. ¶ 80(23). 195 See id. ¶ 136; Rúa, supra note 161, at 239. 196 La Cantuta, 2007 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 162, ¶ 80(44). “On July 7, 1993, in Case No. 157-V-93, the SCMJ Investigation Board extended inquiry proceedings against Brigade General Juan Rivero-Lazo, Cavalry Colonel Federico Augusto Navarro-Pérez, Maj. Santiago En- rique Martín-Rivas, Maj. Carlos Pichilingüe-Guevara and Lt. Aquilino Portella-Nuñez and José Adolfo Velarde-Astete, on the grounds of the alleged commission of abuse of authority and crimes against life, body and health. On December 13, 1993, inquiry proceedings were extended against Infantry Lt. José Adolfo Valarde-Astete ‘to be held responsible for’ the offense of negli- gence . . . .” Id. ¶ 80(43). Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 89EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 lio Salazar-Monroe, and Juan Rivero-Lazo as the masterminds of the La Cantuta crimes.197 The same prosecutor who oversaw the exhumations of the clandestine graves, Cubas-Villanueva, also filed a criminal complaint, which included officers named in the SCMJ investigation, with a court in Lima on December 16, 1993.198 The Lima court started proceedings the next day. The SCMJ then immediately challenged the ordinary court’s jurisdiction.199 But for international pressure, the search for justice may have continued in this endless circle. The international community, however, made La Cantuta a cause célèbre and posed it as the final test of Fujimori’s pledge of democracy and human rights after his self-coup.200 Rising to the occasion made sense for Fujimori given his upcoming bid for reelection and his political need to unfreeze millions of dollars in U.S. aid, which was conditioned on “a satisfactory resolution” of the La Cantuta case.201 As would be later revealed later, he selected a group of officers to stand trial with the promise that they would later be pardoned and handsomely compensated for their sacrifice.202 But the jurisdiction question still awaited final resolution. In the new quest to showcase justice, the administration pushed for a conclusion. The Criminal Chamber of the Peruvian Supreme Court issued a de- cision on the matter on February 3, 1994, but the decision was divided with two justices supporting the ordinary court jurisdiction and the other three supporting the military courts.203 A vote of at least four was needed to approve jurisdiction. In quick response, the Fujimori-backed Congress presented a bill on Febru- ary 8, 1994, proposing that a conflict of jurisdiction issue be resolved by simple majority and secret ballot. The law was designed to be retroactive, thus allowing the previous three affirmative votes to count. The bill was approved the same day and signed into law by Fujimori the next day.204 With the issue of jurisdiction now settled, the military trials proceeded on February 11, 1994.205 The trials resulted in acquittals for some of the defendants on the more serious charges.206 Five offi- cers, however, were convicted on several major counts, including forced disappea- rances, and received prison terms of fifteen to twenty years.207 On May 3, 1994, the SCMJ affirmed the decision.208 The SCMJ War Chambers started proceedings against the alleged “intellectual perpetrators” of La Cantuta, including Army Ge- 197 Id. ¶ 80(45). 198 Id. ¶¶ 80(46)–(47). Cubas-Villanueva soon encountered threats as well as attempts by the same judiciary trying to undermine him with fabricated disciplinary charges. See id. ¶ 80(49). 199 Id. ¶ 80(48). 200 See James Brooke, Army Officers’ Trials to Test Democracy in Peru, N.Y. Times, Jan. 12, 1994, at A3. 201 Id. Rúa reports that the trials were first announced in the New York Times and not local news- papers, evidencing their intent to please an international audience. Rúa, supra note 161, at 242. 202 7 Comisión de la Verdad y Reconciliacion [Truth & Reconciliation Commission], supra note 162, at 241–43, available at http://www.cverdad.org.pe/ifinal/pdf/TOMO%20VII/Casos%20 Ilustrativos-UIE/2.22.%20LA%20CANTUTA.pdf; Ernesto Chávez, Grupo Colina Amenaza y Fu- jimori los Amnistía, Crónica Viva (Oct. 3, 2007) (Peru), at http://www.cronicaviva.com.pe/index. php?option=com_content&task=view&id=18976&Itemid=86. 203 La Cantuta, 2007 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 162, ¶ 80(50). 204 Id. ¶ 80(51) (discussing Law No. 26,291). 205 Id. ¶ 80(52). 206 See id. ¶ 80(54)(a)–(j). 207 See id. ¶ 80(54)(i)–(j). 208 See id. ¶ 80(55). Lisa J. Laplante 90 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 neral Hermoza-Ríos, Brigade Army General Pérez-Documet, and Retired Army Captain Montesinos, on the grounds they committed serious crimes, including forced disappearance, but ultimately decided to dismiss the case on August 15, 1994.209 The SCMJ Review Chamber affirmed this decision on August 18, 1994, and closed the case permanently for lack of evidence.210 Fujimori’s hope that these convictions would persuade critics that justice had been done was not borne out. As foreshadowed by Lourdes Flores, an oppo- sitional member of Congress: “This process is not going to be considered closed because the competence of the military courts was defined through an unconsti- tutional law. Therefore, when democracy is fully recovered, it is very probable that either the Supreme Court or even political pressure will reopen this case.”211 Her prediction would come true, although not for another six years, and only after Fujimori managed to erode further the rule of law. 4.4 A new presidential term and amnesty laws Fujimori won reelection by a landslide in April 1995 despite accusations of corruption.212 Having seemingly laid to rest the scandal surrounding Colina and securing his continuation in office, Fujimori appeared to have guaranteed impu- nity. Any complacency, however, would soon be challenged by public prosecutor Ana Cecilia Magallanes, who opened criminal investigations in April 1995 against five army officials, including General Julio Salazar-Monroe, the head of the Na- tional Intelligence Service, for the massacre at Barrios Altos,213 Judge Antonia Saquicuray of the Sixteenth Criminal Court of Lima initiated a formal investiga- tion on April 19, 1995, yet when she tried to summon the accused to take their statements, the SCMJ issued a resolution barring her request because it conflicted with the SCMJ’s jurisdiction.214 Regardless, Judge Saquicuray pursued the investi- gation, and the military court filed a petition before the Supreme Court to resolve the jurisdictional issue. 215 The Supreme Court never had a chance to deliberate on the issue, ho- wever, because Congress adopted Law No. 26,479 (the “Amnesty Law”) in the early morning hours of June 14, 1995.216 The next day the president immediately promulgated the law.217 The law granted amnesty to “all members of the security 209 Id. ¶ 80(57). The military court did not accept the argument that the officers acted with the approval of high command. Rúa, supra note 161, at 264–65. 210 La Cantuta, 2007 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 162, ¶ 80(57). 211 Nathaniel C. Nash, 9 Peruvian Military Men Are Sentenced in Killings, N.Y. Times, Feb. 22, 1994, at A6. 212 See Conaghan, supra note 152, at 96–99 (describing the 1995 Peruvian elections). See generally Gregory D. Schmidt, Delegative Democracy in Peru? Fujimori’s 1995 Landslide and the Prospects for 2000, 42 J. Interam. Stud. & World Aff. 99 (2000). 213 Barrios Altos Case, 2002 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 75, ¶ 2(g) (Mar. 14, 2001). 214 Id. ¶ 2(h). 215 Id. ¶ 2(i). 216 Id. The law was passed without committee review or debate. See id. See generally Burke-White, supra note 75, at 485–89 (discussing the Peruvian amnesty law and legal challenges). 217 Barrios Altos, 2002 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 75, ¶ 2(i). Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 91EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 forces and civilians who had been accused, investigated, prosecuted or convicted, or who were carrying out prison sentences, for human rights violations.”218 The practical result was that the La Cantuta convictions were immediately annulled, the eight detained members of Colina were released, and all other human rights investigations, including the Barrios Altos case, were barred.219 Despite this abso- lute ban on criminal investigations, Judge Saquicuray decided the next day that Article 1 of Law No. 26,479 was not applicable to Barrios Altos because it viola- ted the Constitution and Peru’s obligations under the American Convention.220 The defense lawyers for the accused in Barrios Altos appealed.221 The Eleventh Criminal Chamber of the Lima Superior Court scheduled a hearing to review the law on July 3, 1995, but before the hearing could take place Congress adopted a second amnesty law which barred judicial review of Law No. 26,479 and made its application obligatory.222 The law also extended immunity to all military, police, or civilian officials who might be the subject of indictments for human rights violations committed between 1980 and 1995.223 In an about turn, the Eleventh Criminal Chamber of the Lima Superior Court overturned the lower court’s deci- sion that the first amnesty law was unconstitutional and quashed the Barrios Altos investigation on July 14, 1995.224 It also declared that the court was barred from reviewing the law due to the principle of separation of powers and ordered an investigation of Judge Saquicuray.225 Eventually, the Tribunal Constitucional, Peru’s highest court, suggested in a 1997 opinion that the amnesty laws were unconsti- tutional, but in subservience to the authoritarian regime avoided issuing a final sentence on the matter and declared that it lacked jurisdiction to hear the merits given that the second amnesty law barred judicial review.226 On July 28, 1995, when Fujimori was sworn into office for the second time, he asked for a minute of silence for all the victims, and then addressed the nation: “We must pacify our hearts, and forget the past and honor the memory of all of our dece- ased, because all of us, right or wrong, are Peruvians! The amnesty law is necessary to build peace, and so Peruvians must not look back but instead to the future.”227 218 Id. 219 See id.; La Cantuta Case, 2007 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 162, ¶¶ 80(59)–(60) (Nov. 29, 2006). 220 Barrios Altos, 2002 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 75, ¶ 2(k). The Peruvian Constitution requires judges not to apply “those laws that they consider contrary to the provisions of the Constitution.” Id. 221 Id. ¶ 2(l). 222 Id. ¶ 2(m). 223 Id. 224 Id. ¶ 2(n). 225 Id; see also Susana Villarán de la Puente, Peru, in Victims Unsilenced: The Inter-American Hu- man Rights System and Transitional Justice in Latin America, supra note 39, at 116 (providing the author’s first-hand account of the court decision). 226 See Constitutional Court, Exp. No. 013-96-I/TC (Apr. 18 1997) (Peru); see also Roht-Arriaza & Gibson, supra note 31, at 878–79 (discussing the Peruvian Supreme Court’s rationale of “separation of powers” in declining jurisdiction). 227 Rúa, supra note 161, at 280. Lisa J. Laplante 92 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 4.5 The inter-american system of human rights and fujimori’s downfall Those who suffered under Fujimori’s regime were not ready to forget the experience so easily. Faced with domestic judicial remedies that were wholly ina- dequate, the victim-survivors began to take their claims to the IACHR with the help of human rights defenders. The human rights lawyers of the National Co- ordinator of Human Rights filed a petition against the government on June 30, 1995, for the issuance of the amnesty laws that obstructed a full and fair criminal investigation and trial of those responsible for the Barrios Altos massacre.228 At that time, a petition for the La Cantuta massacre was already pending with the IACHR pursuant to a filing made on July 30, 1992, by Gisela Ortiz-Perea, Rosario Muñoz-Sánchez, Raida Cóndor, José Oyague, and Bitalia Barrueta de Pablo based on the same concern regarding the futility of internal remedies.229 Indeed, a steady stream of petitions from Peruvians caught in Fujimori’s Machiavellian web began to flow through the doors of the IACHR, especially as local human rights organizations began to use this international forum to advance their local struggle.230 The IACHR, in turn, began to present the most emblema- tic of these cases to the contentious jurisdiction of the IACtHR.231 Soon after Fujimori’s second election, the IACtHR issued landmark decisions concerning many of the abusive trademarks of Fujimori’s regime, including forced disappe- arances, prison massacres, and the arbitrary and unjust imprisonment of people under the state’s antiterrorist legislation.232 Fujimori’s government came under heightened scrutiny as the decisions sig- naled a clear condemnation of its policies and practices for failing to uphold the American Convention. As already noted, Fujimori’s government worried about the international community’s opinion, in particular that of the United States, and thus it could not so easily ignore the international court. Peru thus began to adhere reluctantly and only partially to the Court’s orders. After the Court began directly to question the government’s national security laws, however, Fujimori 228 Barrios Altos, 2002 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 75, ¶ 4. The IACHR registered the case as No. 11.528 on August 28, 1995, and requested information from the state within ninety days. Subsequent petitions were submitted on behalf of the victims and next of kin over the following year, all of which were joined to the original petition. See id. ¶¶ 4–10. 229 See La Cantuta Case, 2007 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 162, ¶ 5 (Nov. 29, 2006). The case was registered as No. 11.045 by the IACHR. Eventually other petitions filed by the human rights organization, Asociación Pro Derechos Humanos, would be joined to it, and a session on the admissibility of the case occurred on March 11, 1999. Id. ¶¶ 5–8. 230 For a fuller account of this history, see generally Laplante, supra note 149. 231 The Inter-American Commission filters cases to the Inter-American Court. Applicants do not have the right to bring a case directly to the IACtHR under the American Convention. See Pasqualucci, supra note 107, at 360–61. 232 See, e.g., Durand & Ugarte Case, 2001 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 68 (Aug. 16, 2000) (concerning the prison massacre at El Frontón); Cesti-Hurtado Case, 2000 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 56 (Sept. 29, 1999); Castillo-Páez Case, 1998 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 34 (Nov. 3, 1997) (concerning the forced disappearance of a university student); Loayza-Tamayo Case, 1998 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 33 (Sept. 17, 1997) (dealing with arbitrary impris- onment and torture under antiterrorism law). Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 93EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 withdrew from the Court’s jurisdiction in July 1999, a decision declared invalid by the Court.233 This defiant act put Peru under greater international scrutiny and contributed to the cascade of events that would cause Fujimori’s downfall shortly after his fraudulent 2000 reelection.234 5 A new paradigm: peru’s political transition without amnesty Soon after the 2000 Peruvian elections, Fujimori’s regime came to an abrupt end due to corruption scandals. Hundreds of videos were uncovered show- ing Montesinos bribing the country’s powerful elites (including those in media, business, and military), forcing Fujimori to call for new elections in which he pledged not to run.235 In November 2000, before those elections took place, Fu- jimori travelled to Japan, faxed his resignation, and proceeded to take refuge for five years despite Peru’s efforts to extradite him to stand trial for his abuses.236 In this sudden political clearing, Peru initiated a process of transitional justice to address the human and institutional damage caused by the conflict. In the same month that Fujimori became a fugitive, the transitional govern- ment led by Valentín Paniagua sought to legitimize itself by mending relations with the Inter-American System.237 The government began a massive sweep to prosecute the individuals caught in Montesinos and Fujimori’s intricate corruption scheme, and, as part of this new intiative, brought charges against the Supreme Court jus- tices who dismissed the La Cantuta case for personal cover up and criminal asso- ciation.238 Peru rejoined the contentious jurisdiction of the IACtHR and began to 233 See Morse Tan, Member State Compliance with the Judgments of the Inter-American Court of Human Rights, 33 Int’l J. Legal Info. 319, 322–25 (2005) (describing Fujimori’s attempt to withdraw from the IACtHR). For the Court’s rejection of this withdrawal, see also Ivcher-Bronstein Case, 2000 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 54 (Sept. 24, 1999). 234 The legitimacy of Fujimori’s 2000 reelection was questioned even more so than his first reelection in 1995. In order to run for a third term, Fujimori solicited Congress to issue an inter- pretation of the Peruvian Constitution that permitted a third term. The climate of the elections also included political repression which led to condemnation from international observers sent from the OAS. See Press Release, Inter-American Commission on Human Rights, Report by the IACHR on the Situation of Human Rights in Peru (June 4, 2000), at http://www.cidh.oas.org/ Comunicados/English/2000/Press6-00.htm. See generally Andrew F. Cooper & Thomas Legler, The OAS in Peru: A Model for the Future?, 12 J. Democracy 123 (2001) (providing a comprehen- sive narrative of the 2000 elections and discussing its legal flaws). For international press cover- age, see, for example, Andres Oppenheimer, Watchdog Group May Condemn Peru Election, Miami Herald, Mar. 25, 2000, at A3. 235 See generally John McMillan & Pablo Zoido, How to Subvert Democracy: Montesinos in Peru, 18 J. Econ. Persp. 69 (2004) (describing the events, including the secret videos, that led to Fujimori’s downfall). 236 John R. Hamilton, The Fall of Fujimori: A Diplomat’s Perspective, 30 Fletcher Foreign World Aff. 191, 191 (2006). 237 Laplante, supra note 149, at 222. 238 La Cantuta Case, 2007 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 162, ¶¶ 80(71)–(74) (Nov. 29, 2006). For a general discussion of the corruption trials, see Nelly Calderón Navarro, Fighting Corruption: The Peruvian Experience, 4 J. Int’l Crim. Just. 488 (2006) (describing the special criminal court created to try hundreds of Peruvians on charges of corruption). Lisa J. Laplante 94 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 comply with its previous judgments.239 In February 2001, Peru sought to resolve a great number of the cases still being processed by the IACHR, including La Cantuta, through a “friendly settlement,” in which the state promised not only to pay repara- tions to the victims and next of kin, but also to initiate investigations.240 The tran- sitional government realized that, in addition to these cases, there were thousands more that could lead to new petitions. It thus sought a more comprehensive and administrative means of addressing them, namely by way of a truth commission. In December 2001, the transitional government created the Inter-Institu- tional Working Group, which ultimately led to the establishment of the TRC.241 The Inter-Institutional Working Group envisioned that the TRC would address “events attributable to State agents, events attributable to individuals who acted with State agents’ consent, acquiescence or connivance, as well as those events that are attributable to subversive groups,” a focus eventually included in the mandate approved by executive decree.242 In committing to criminal justice, how- ever, the transitional government faced the immediate challenge of Fujimori’s 1995 amnesty laws. If future prosecution remained impossible, the TRC might fail to meet the expectations of victims. Moreover, if the amnesty laws forbade all types of investigation, the TRC’s investigations could also be thwarted by Fujimori’s supporters and the military because they still enjoyed substantial po- wer. Aware that a domestic solution would be not be feasible in the short term, Peru looked to the Inter-American System for a resolution. 239 Resolución Legislativa No. 27,401, Diario Oficial El Peruano No. 197,465 (Jan. 19, 2001) (Peru) (abrogating Legislative Resolution No. 27,152). 240 A friendly settlement is an agreement between the parties to settle the case with- out the Court deciding on its merits. Peru agreed to settle more than 165 cases, represent- ing over half of its total cases then before the IACHR. See Joint Press Release, Inter-Amer- ican Commission on Human Rights, Meeting with Representatives of the Government of Peru (Feb. 22, 2001), at http://www.cidh.org/Comunicados/English/2001/Peru.htm; Org. of Am. States, Report of the Permanent Council on the Observations and Recommendations of the Member States on the 2001 Annual Report of The Inter-American Commission on Human Rights, OEA/Ser.G/CP/Doc.3612/02, at 21–22 (May 23, 2002), available at http://scm.oas.org/ doc_public/ENGLISH/HIST_02/CP09961E07.DOC. See generally Patricia E. Standaert, The Friendly Settlement of Human Rights Abuses in the Americas, 9 Duke J. Comp. & Int’l L. 519 (1999) (providing an explanation of the “friendly settlement” mechanism). 241 Participating in the deliberations were the Ministries of Justice, Interior, Defense, Pro- motion of Women and Human Development, as well as the People’s Ombudsman, the Pe- ruvian Episcopal Conference, the Peruvian Evangelist Association, and the National Hu- man Rights Coordinating Committee. See 1 Comisión de la Verdad y Reconciliacion [Truth & Reconciliation Commission], supra note 162, at 22, available at http://www.cverdad.org.pe/ ifinal/pdf/TOMO%20I/INTRODUCCION.pdf. 242 Id. at 23 (“[T]anto los hechos imputables a agentes del Estado, a las personas que actuaron bajo su consentimiento, aquiescencia o complicidad, así como los imputables a los grupos sub- versives.”) (author’s translation). The crimes to be investigated included: (a) murder and abduc- tion; (b) forced disappearance; (c) torture and other severe injuries; (d) violation of collective rights of Andean Communities and Communities native to the country; and (e) other crimes and severe violations of the rights of persons. 1 Comisión de la Verdad y Reconciliacion [Truth & Reconciliation Commission], supra note 162, at 195, available at http://www.cverdad.org.pe/ ifinal (follow “Capítulo 4: La dimensión jurídica de los hechos” hyperlink under “Tomo I”). Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 95EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 5.1 Where the international meets the national Recalling the failed attempt to defeat amnesty laws in South Africa, John Dugard points out that where national legal remedies proved inadequate, hu- man rights advocates in South Africa did not have recourse to international legal bodies in the way their counterparts in Latin America did as a result of those countries’ membership in the Inter-American System.243 Indeed, despite the state practice in Latin America of implementing amnesties, the Inter-American System consistently condemned this trend.244 Before the fall of Fujimori’s regime, the IACHR had an opportunity to deliberate on the Barrios Altos case and evidenced its consistent condemnation of amnesties. It adopted Report No. 28/00 after Peru failed to reach a friendly settlement, recommending that the state annul any domestic, legislative or any other measure aimed at pre- venting the investigation, prosecution and punishment of those re- sponsible for the assassinations and injuries resulting from the events known as the “Barrios Altos” operation. To this end, the State of Peru should abrogate Amnesty Laws Nos. 26,479 and 26,492.245 It further recommended that the state conduct a serious, impartial and effective investigation into the facts, in order to identify those responsible for the assassinations and injuries in this case, and continue with the judicial prosecu- tion of Julio Salazar Monroe, Santiago Martín Rivas, Nelson Car- bajal García, Juan Sosa Saavedra and Hugo Coral Goycochea, and punish those responsible for these grave crimes, through the cor- responding criminal procedure, in accordance with the law.246 Peru, however, refused to follow the recommendations and explained in a communication on May 9, 2000, that the amnesty laws were exceptional me- asures in response to terrorist violence, relying on the Peruvian Constitutional Court’s ruling.247 With no other recourse, the IACHR decided to submit the case to the IACtHR on May 10, 2000, despite Peru’s alleged withdrawal from the Court’s contentious jurisdiction.248 In response to the Court’s proceedings, repre- 243 See Dugard, supra note 60, at 282–85. 244 See generally Cassel, supra note 115 (describing the OAS’s reaction to amnesties in Latin American countries); Robert Kogod Goldman, Amnesty Laws, International Law and the American Convention on Human Rights, 6 Law Group Docket, Summer 1989, at 1; Robert K. Goldman, Uruguay: Amnesty Law in Violation of Human Rights Convention, 49 Rev. Int’l Commission Jurists 37 (1992). 245 Barrios Altos Case, 2002 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 75, ¶ 17 (Mar. 14, 2001) (quoting Chumbipuma Aguirre et al. v. Peru, Cases 11.528, 11.601, Inter-Am. C.H.R., Report No. 28/00, OEA/Ser./L/V/II.111, doc. 20 rev. (2000)). 246 Id. (quoting Chumbipuma Aguirre et al. v. Peru, Cases 11.528, 11.601, Inter-Am. C.H.R., Report No. 28/00, OEA/Ser./L/V/II.111, doc. 20 rev. (2000)). 247 Id. ¶ 18. 248 See id. ¶ 19. Lisa J. Laplante 96 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 sentatives of the Peruvian Embassy in Costa Rica communicated with the Court’s Secretariat on August 24, 2000, reminding the Court of Peru’s withdrawal.249 Peru concluded that the immediate effect of this withdrawal upon deposit was that the IACtHR no longer had competence to hear an application against Peru due to lack of jurisdiction.250 The Court responded by reminding Peru that the Court had already rejected the withdrawal in the Ivcher Bronstein and Consti- tutional Court cases,251 and that in its opinion the “attitude of the State of Peru constitutes a clear failure to comply with Article 68(1) of the Convention, and also a violation of the basic principle pacta sunt servanda.” 252 The case remained in limbo until Fujimori’s regime fell, and Peru reinstated its recognition of the Court’s contentious jurisdiction on January 23, 2001. This permitted the Barrios Altos case, and others, to go forward. In fact, with the time pressure of the TRC’s pending formation, the Peruvian government sought to expedite the case and persuaded the Inter-American Commission to press the Court to speed its deci- sion despite its fears that the IACtHR might depart from the Commission’s own evolving jurisprudence against amnesties.253 5.2 The barrios altos decision The IACtHR convened a public hearing on March 14, 2001 to hear the merits of the Barrios Altos case, during which Peru explained: [T]he Government’s strategy in the area of human rights is based on recognizing responsibilities, but, above all, on proposing in- tegrated procedures for attending to the victims based on three fundamental elements: the right to truth, the right to justice and the right to obtain fair reparation. […] […] [With regard to the] Barrios Altos case […] substantial mea- sures have been taken to ensure that criminal justice will make a prompt decision on this case. However, we are faced with […] an obstacle […] we refer to the amnesty laws. The amnesty laws […] directly entailed a violation of the right of all victims to obtain not only justice but also truth. . . . Consequently, the Govern- ment of Peru has suggested to the original petitioners, that is, the National Human Rights Coordinator, the possibility of advancing with friendly settlements, which entail effective solutions to this procedural obstacle […]254 249 Id. ¶ 25. 250 Id. 251 Id. ¶ 27; see also Ivcher-Bronstein Case, 2000 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 54 (Sept. 24, 1999); Constitutional Court Case, 2000 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 55 (Sept. 24, 1999). 252 Barrios Altos, 2002 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 75, ¶ 27 (citations omitted). 253 See id. ¶ 35. For a fuller account of this history see Laplante, supra note 149, at 222–23. (de- scribing the Peruvian government’s strategy in approaching the IACtHR). 254 Barrios Altos, 2002 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 75, ¶ 35. Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 97EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 Peru, then, set the tone of its transitional justice project to include criminal justice. It proposed, among other things, a “preliminary agenda” based on the following three points: “identification of mechanisms to fully clarify the facts on which the petition was based, including identification of the masterminds and perpetrators of the crime, the viability of criminal and administrative punish- ments for all those found responsible, and specific proposals and agreements on matters relating to reparations.”255 The state, perhaps betraying its own newfound eagerness to annul the pre- vious government’s “mechanisms of impunity,” suggested “the parties should re- quest the Inter-American Court to deliver the judgment on the merits immedia- tely, establishing the international responsibility as determined by the Court and taking into account the brief on acquiescence that had been submitted.”256 The IACHR, in turn, emphasized that the Court had a special opportunity, a truly historic opportunity, to advance inter- national human rights law, based on measures under domestic law that contribute to combat impunity, which is one of the evils of our hemisphere, to which this Court and . . . the Commission have ac- corded fundamental importance. I believe that this attitude of the Government of Peru gives us the opportunity to associate ourselves with the people of Peru, their Government and their civil society, to find creative solutions, which may subsequently be emulated and imitated throughout the hemisphere and beyond it.257 The Commission continued by pointing out that the case is “very serious and very sad,” because not only did the state act “unlawfully and clandestine- ly,” but it also deliberately imposed “legislative and judicial mechanisms to pre- vent the facts [surrounding the gruesome events at Barrios Altos] from being known.”258 With the fortuitous change of conditions, the Commission characte- rized the circumstances as “ripe” for an international pronouncement that would provide Peru with an instrument “to destroy and remove the remaining obstacles in order to combat impunity in Peru.”259 One could sense the earnest desire of the IACHR to have the Court back the Commission’s own growing jurisprudence on the issue, that did not enjoy the same binding effect as decisions of the Court. The gamble paid off, though, and that same day the Court issued its judgment stating that the self-amnesty laws were invalid.260 The decision came a mere month before Peru’s transitional gover- nment concluded its negotiations regarding the TRC’s mandate. 255 Id. 256 Id. 257 Id. ¶ 36. 258 Id. 259 Id. 260 Id. ¶¶ 43–44. Lisa J. Laplante 98 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 5.3 The iacthr’s ruling and interpretation The IACtHR did not have much to deliberate on after the state acquiesced to the claims of the petitioners, which meant the Court, pursuant to Article 52(2), only needed to decide the acceptability of this admission of responsibility.261 It began with the question of whether Peru’s amnesty laws were compatible with the American Convention on Human Rights, and concluded with the now frequently cited opinion: This Court considers that all amnesty provisions, provisions on prescription and the establishment of measures designed to elimi- nate responsibility are inadmissible, because they are intended to prevent the investigation and punishment of those responsible for serious human rights violations such as torture, extrajudicial, sum- mary or arbitrary execution and forced disappearance, all of them prohibited because they violate non-derogable rights recognized by international human rights law.262 The Court explained that the amnesty laws prevented survivors and vic- tims’ families from exercising their right to be heard by a judge, to receive judicial protection, and to obtain the investigation, capture, prosecution, and conviction of those responsible for the violations, as protected by Articles 8(1), 25, and 1(1) of the American Convention respectively.263 It further held that those rights should be read together with Articles 1(1) and 2 of the American Convention, which oblige State Parties to “take all measures to ensure that no one is depri- ved of judicial protection and the exercise of the right to a simple and effective recourse . . . .”264 Furthermore, the Court clarified that the amnesty laws also con- travene the obligation to adapt internal legislation to international human rights obligations, as embodied in Article 2 of the American Convention.265 In this way, the Court held that “[s]elf-amnesty laws . . . are manifestly incompatible with the aims and spirit of the Convention . . . because [this type of law] obstructs the investigation and access to justice and prevents the victims and their next of kin from knowing the truth and receiving the corresponding reparation.”266 The laws thus “lack legal effect.”267 The Court turned lastly to the right to truth. The Court agreed with the IACHR that the right to truth is based on Articles 8 and 25 of the Convention: [T]he right to the truth is subsumed in the right of the victim or his next of kin to obtain clarification of the events that violated human rights and the corresponding responsibilities from the competent 261 Id. ¶ 37. 262 Id. ¶ 41. 263 Id. ¶ 42. 264 Id. ¶ 43. 265 See id. 266 Id. ¶ 43. 267 Id. ¶ 44. Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 99EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 organs of the State, through the investigation and prosecution that are established in Articles 8 and 25 of the Convention.268 The IACHR had also argued that the right to truth was supported by Arti- cle 13(1), which provides the right to information, but the Court rested its opi- nion solely on Articles 8 and 25.269 Arguably, the Court’s ruling contributes to the idea that truth and justice are not incompatible, but on the contrary inextricably linked. Its decision stands for the proposition that in a transitional justice fra- mework, prosecutions become another indispensable tool for reaching the truth, a task formerly delegated to truth commissions alone. While the Barrios Altos decision signaled a clear victory for both the tran- sitional government and the IACHR, it was unclear whether the decision offered a general pronouncement or was only specific to the investigation in the Barrios Altos case. Several months after the decision, the IACHR, at the request of Peru, filed for a clarification of the “meaning and scope” of operative paragraph 4 of the Barrios Altos judgment in which the Court declared that “Amnesty Laws No. 26479 and No. 26492 are incompatible with the American Convention on Hu- man Rights and, consequently, lack legal effect.”270 The resulting interpretation confirmed that “the effects of the decision in the judgment on the merits of the Barrios Altos Cases are general in nature.”271 The Court issued its judgment on September 3, 2001, just days before the TRC was scheduled to open its doors for operation, thus providing the TRC a green light not only to initiate its own in- vestigations, but also to collaborate with the Attorney General’s office in bringing charges against specific perpetrators.272 6 Interpreting barrios altos: a bar to amnesty for human rights violations Curiously, despite its potentially sweeping effect on the legitimacy of am- nesties in political transitions, the IACtHR’s Barrios Altos decision has thus far 268 Id. ¶¶ 45–48. 269 Id. 270 Barrios Altos Case, Interpretation of the Judgment of the Merits, 2002 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 83, ¶¶ 8, 16 (Sept. 3, 2001). 271 Id. ¶ 18. The IACHR, in its arguments on the matter, rightly pointed out that the Court already made this clear in paragraph 44 of its decision on the merits. Id. ¶ 14. There, the Court had pronounced: “Owing to the manifest incompatibility of self-amnesty laws and the American Convention on Human Rights, the said laws lack legal effect and may not continue to obstruct the investigation of the grounds on which this case is based or the identification and punish- ment of those responsible, nor can they have the same or a similar impact with regard to other cases that have occurred in Peru, where the rights established in the American Convention have been violated.” Barrios Altos, 2002 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 75, ¶ 44. The request for clarification may thus seem odd, except it could be understood as a desire to preempt any future debate on the matter. Arguably, it also permitted the Court to suggest that any amnesty law would be found incompatible, as is discussed in this Section. 272 In its final report, the TRC acknowledged the important precedent established by the Court. See Hatun Willakuy, Versión Abreviada del Informe Final de la Comisión de la Verdad y Rec- onciliación [Summary version of the Final Report of the Truth & Reconciliation Commission] 31–32 (2003) (Peru). Lisa J. Laplante 100 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 received scant attention from academics, whether from the field of transitional justice or international criminal law. This Part describes the ways in which the Barrios Altos decision has so far been narrowly interpreted and responds with a counteranalysis, including an examination of subsequent IACtHR decisions, whi- ch suggests a much broader reading of this landmark decision. In particular, this Part argues that Barrios Altos: (1) applies to all amnesties and not just self-amnes- ties; (2) requires that criminal investigations not be substituted for other types of noncriminal investigations; and (3) applies to all serious human rights violations and not only crimes against humanity. 6.1 Not limited only to self-amnesty laws One reason for the narrow reading of the Barrios Altos decision may relate to the possible interpretation of the holding as applying only to “self-amnesties.”273 A strict reading of the word “self ” would imply that the Court’s ruling applies only to those laws adopted by the same government seeking immunity from criminal prosecution. This narrow interpretation would mean that amnesties promulgated by subsequent governments, especially if part of an internal peace negotiation process or transitional justice scheme, would be permissible. In addition, it would support the restorative justice view of the truth v. justice debate, which argues that alterna- tive investigatory methods such as truth commissions fulfill the state’s obligation to “ensure” a victim’s human right to justice. Scharf adopted this position in 1996, prior to the 2001 Barrios Altos decision, but nevertheless set the distinction between “self ” and all other amnesties that would later be applied to Barrios Altos.274 A close reading of both the Judgment on the Merits and the subsequent Interpretation of the Judgment, however, suggests a much broader interpretation that prohibits all amnesties, not just self-amnesties. This broader interpretation can be reached by reading the majority opinion together with the concurring opinions of both Judge A.A. Cançado Trindade, former president of the Court, and Judge Sergio García Ramírez, the Court’s current president. Judge Cançado Trindade, in a concurring opinion longer than the majority’s, elaborates his view that the Barrios Altos case represents 273 Barrios Altos, 2002 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 75, ¶¶ 42–44 (emphasis added). While the court does not consistently use this term, it does appear in selected paragraphs in its decision on the merits. See, e.g., id. For a discussion of the different types of amnesties, see Young, supra note 4, at 216 (explaining that the three types include “self amnesty, amnesties granted to end political or military conflict, and amnesty in exchange for facts and information surrounding specific crimes”). 274 See Scharf, supra note 105, at 61. (“[I]t is likely that the . . . Inter-American Court of Human Rights would . . . agree that measures short of prosecution . . . would be adequate to discharge the duty to ensure human rights.”). Scharf repeated this argument in 2006, yet did not mention Barrios Altos or the subsequent rulings of the IACtHR that reinforce the general obligation to pursue criminal trials for human rights violations that do not necessarily fall within the strict criteria of being a crime found in a treaty. See Scharf, supra note 103, at 358. This limited inter- pretation is also adopted by Elizabeth Evenson. See Elizabeth M. Evenson, Note, Truth and Justice in Sierra Leone: Coordination Between Commission and Court, 104 Colum. L. Rev. 730, 750 n.127 (2004) (interpreting Barrios Altos as applicable only to “self-amnesty” laws). Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 101EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 a new and great qualitative step forward in its case-law, to the ef- fect of seeking to overcome an obstacle which the international organs of supervision of human rights have not yet succeeded to surpass: the impunity, with the resulting erosion of the confidence of the population in public institutions. Moreover, they meet an expectation which in our days is truly universal. It may be recalled, in this respect, that the main document adopted by the II World Conference of Human Rights (1993) urged the States to “abrogate legislation leading to impunity for those responsible for grave vio- lations of human rights […] and prosecute such violations […]”275 Significantly, Judge Cançado Trindade refers to a bedrock principle of inter- national law: that domestic laws may not be used to avoid international obliga- tions.276 He has also consistently written in other dissenting and concurring opi- nions that international law trumps national domestic law.277 This interpretation means that any type of immunity measure, including amnesties, made at any time to obstruct human rights prosecutions (which are now considered a state duty due to the Velásquez Rodríguez decision) would be invalid. Admittedly, Judge Cançado Trindade’s concurring opinion in Barrios Altos may only be read as his alone. However, the IACtHR adopted this same position in its subsequent interpretation of Barrios Altos—an interpretation astutely re- quested by Peru. In its interpretation, the Court reiterated its position that the ru- ling on amnesties applies to all criminal cases arising out of Peru’s internal armed conflict, not just Barrios Altos. The Court also referred to its case-law: [T]he general obligation of the State, established in Article 2 of the Convention, includes the adoption of measures to suppress laws and practices of any kind that imply a violation of the guar- antees established in the Convention, and also the adoption of laws and the implementation of practices leading to the effective observance of the said guarantees. […] In international law, customary law establishes that a State which has ratified a human rights treaty must introduce the neces- sary modifications to its domestic law to ensure the proper com- pliance with the obligations it has assumed. This law is universally accepted and is supported by jurisprudence. The American Con- vention establishes the general obligation of each State Party to 275 Barrios Altos, 2002 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 75, ¶ 4 (Cançado Trindade, J., concur- ring) (quoting World Conference on Human Rights, June 14–25, 1993, Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action, ¶ 60, U.N. Doc. A/CONF.157/23 (July 12, 1993)) (referring to the criticisms of the “ignored amnesties” of the past). 276 Judge Cançado Trindade writes: “[These laws are] in flagrant incompatibility with the norms of protection of the International Law of Human Rights, bringing about violations de jure of the rights of the human person. The corpus juris of the International Law of Human Rights makes it clear that not everything that is lawful in the domestic legal order is so in the international legal order, and even more forcefully when superior values (such as truth and justice) are at stake. In reality, what came to be called laws of amnesty, and particularly the perverse modality of the so- called laws of self-amnesty, even if they are considered laws under a given domestic legal order, are not so in the ambit of the International Law of Human Rights.” Id. ¶ 6. 277 Id. ¶¶ 7–9. Lisa J. Laplante 102 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 adapt its domestic law to the provisions of this Convention, in order to guarantee the rights that it embodies. This general ob- ligation of the State Party implies that the measures of domestic law must be effective (the principle of effet utile). This means that the State must adopt all measures so that the provisions of the Convention are effectively fulfilled in its domestic legal system, as Article 2 of the Convention requires. Such measures are only effective when the State adjusts its actions to the Convention’s rules on protection.278 The Court’s subsequent interpretation of its own decision in Barrios Altos can be read to extend its ruling to all amnesties, not just self-amnesties. This rea- ding supports the other concurring opinion in Barrios Altos made by Judge García Ramírez who, also adhering to his previous concurring opinions, notes that one can distinguish between self-amnesty laws “promulgated by and for those in po- wer,” and those […] that are the result of a peace process, have a democratic base and a reasonable scope, that preclude prosecution of acts or be- haviors of members of rival factions, but leave open the possibility of punishment for the kind of very egregious acts that no faction either approves or views as appropriate.279 Significantly, he goes on to recognize “the advisability of encouraging ci- vic harmony through amnesty laws that contribute to re-establishing peace and opening new constructive stages in the life of a nation.”280 Nonetheless, he reite- rates the opinion of the “growing sector of doctrine and also the Inter-American Court” that “such forgive and forget provisions ‘cannot be permitted to cover up the most severe human rights violations, violations that constitute an utter disregard for the dignity of the human being and are repugnant to the conscience of humanity.’”281 Judge García Ramírez also refers to the principle embodied in Articles 1(1) and 2 of the Convention that states may not “invoke ‘difficulties of a domestic nature’ to waive the obligation to investigate the facts that infringed the Convention and punish those who are found criminally responsible for them.”282 If there is any question as to the actual reach of the Barrios Altos decision, subsequent IACtHR rulings confirm the broader interpretation. For example, the Bulacio case reinforces the notion that domestic laws preventing prosecution of human rights violations, including amnesty laws, are barred.283 In Bulacio, Argen- 278 Barrios Altos Case, Interpretation of the Judgment on the Merits, 2002 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 83, ¶ 17 (Sept. 3, 2001) (citations omitted). 279 Barrios Altos, 2002 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 75, ¶ 10 (García Ramírez, J., concurring). 280 Id. ¶ 11. 281 Id. 282 Id. ¶ 12. 283 Bulacio Case, 2004 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 100 (Sept. 18, 2004). This case involved a complaint brought against the state of Argentina for the death of a seventeen-year-old boy who was detained during a general roundup of adolescents before a rock concert and later beaten up by police. Id. ¶ 3. See generally Basch, supra note 115, at 207–16 (discussing Bulacio and its impli- cations for the duty to prosecute doctrine). Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 103EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 tina acknowledged responsibility for the death of a minor and accepted that it had violated the right to life and humane treatment.284 Argentina also accepted res- ponsibility for violating Articles 8 and 25 by failing to provide an effective remedy in the form of a prompt investigation and punishment of those responsible.285 The IACtHR was left with the task of determining the appropriate reparations, including the duty to investigate the human rights violation.286 The IACtHR determined that the failure to investigate the case in Argen- tina had “been tolerated and allowed by the intervening judiciary bodies,” which acted as though their function was limited only to assuring due process in the form of a guaranteed defense at a trial.287 In the domestic case, the defense coun- sel was allowed to use delaying tactics which stalled the trial for several years and ultimately gave rise to a plea for extinguishment of the criminal case.288 Relying on the Barrios Altos interpretation, the Court also held: [E]xtinguishment provisions or any other domestic legal obstacle that attempts to impede the investigation and punishment of those responsible for human rights violations are inadmissible. The Court deems that the general obligations enshrined in Articles 1(1) and 2 of the American Convention require that the States Party adopt timely provisions of all types for no one to be denied the right to judicial protection, enshrined in Article 25 of the American Convention.289 The Court reiterated that Article 27 of the 1969 Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties prohibits domestic legal rules, such as extinguishment pro- visions, from hindering the full application of decisions by international human rights bodies.290 According to the Court: “If that were not the case, the rights enshrined in the American Convention would be devoid of effective protection. This understanding of the Court is in accordance with the language and the spirit of the Convention, as well as the general principles of law.” 291 The Court further explained that “a situation of grave impunity” existed in Argentina due to the fact that no one there had yet been convicted, despite the initiation of judicial proce- edings nearly twelve years earlier.292 The Court characterized “impunity” as […] the overall lack of investigation, pursuit, capture, trial and conviction of those responsible for violations of rights protected 284 See Bulacio, 2004 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 100, ¶¶ 25, 33. 285 See id. ¶ 33. For instance, the case against one police officer was delayed for several years largely due to the fact that “defense counsel for the accused filed a large number of diverse legal questions and remedies (requests for postponement, challenges, incidental pleas, objections, motions on lack of jurisdiction, requests for annulment, among others), which have not allowed the proceedings to progress toward their natural culmination, which has given rise to a plea for extinguishment of the criminal action.” Bulacio, 2004 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 100, ¶ 113. 286 See id. ¶¶ 34, 110. 287 Id. ¶ 114. 288 Id. ¶ 113. 289 Id. ¶ 116 (citations omitted). 290 Id. ¶ 118. For a general discussion of the domestic law prohibition, see Henrard, supra note 78. 291 Bulacio, 2004 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 100, ¶ 117 (citation omitted). 292 Id. ¶ 119. Lisa J. Laplante 104 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 under the American Convention, as the State has the obligation to combat said situation by all legal means within its power, as impu- nity fosters chronic recidivism of human rights violations and total defenselessness of the victims and of their next of kin.293 The Court reaffirmed its view that domestic immunity measures such as am- nesty would impede the state’s duty to investigate and punish perpetrators of hu- man rights violations in Moiwana Community v. Suriname in 2005.294 There, the Court emphasized that Suriname’s amnesty laws would deprive its people of the effective protections of the American Convention and ordered the laws to be repealed. 295 The Court reiterated the “domestic law” prohibition against amnesties again in the La Cantuta decision in 2006. In that decision, the IACtHR said the Article 2 provision, which prohibits domestic laws from being used to avoid in- ternational legal obligations, “is universally valid and has been characterized in case law as an evident principle.”296 As a result, states must adjust their internal domestic laws to guarantee the rights enshrined in the Convention, and these laws must be effective pursuant to the effet utile principle.297 While the Court in La Cantuta did not identify specific domestic measures that may require adjust- ment, it did offer two general measures which should be adopted: “(i) repealing rules and practices of any nature involving violations to the guarantees provided for in the Convention or disregarding the rights enshrined therein or hamper the exercise of such rights, and (ii) issuing rules and developing practices aimed at effectively observing said guarantees.”298 Thus, these general guidelines, if applied to the case of amnesty laws would require their being repealed. 6.2 Other investigations cannot substitute for criminal investigations A narrow reading of the Barrios Altos decision might interpret it to apply only to blanket amnesties that prohibit all forms of investigation.299 Trumbull argues the Court may have left open the possibility that a state could satisfy its general obligation to afford accountability so long as it conducted some type of investigation, even if not pursuant to a criminal prosecution.300 He also indicates in a footnote that Peru did eventually conduct investigations through the TRC in 293 Id. ¶ 120 (citation omitted). 294 Moiwana Community Case, 2006 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 124, ¶ 167 (June 15, 2005). 295 See id. ¶ 207. 296 La Cantuta Case, 2007 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 162, ¶ 170 (Nov. 29, 2006) (citation omitted). 297 Id. ¶ 171 (citations omitted). 298 Id. ¶ 172 (citations omitted). 299 Trumbull, supra note 43, at 300–01 (suggesting that blanket amnesties that bar all investiga- tions are not lawful and that states must provide some form of accountability for human rights atrocities). 300 Id.; see also Richard J. Wilson & Jan Perlin, The Inter-American Human Rights System: Activities from Late 2000 Through October 2002, 18 Am. U. Int’l L. Rev. 651, 657 (2003) (suggesting that the Court’s holding may be interpreted to mean some form of investigation is necessary). Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 105EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 the absence of criminal prosecutions, and implies that the IACtHR approved of this arrangement, supporting his view. 301 Trumbull’s interpretation may be refuted, though, by subsequent decisions of the IACtHR. For example, the Court reiterated the general prohibition on am- nesties in Cantoral-Huamaní and García-Santa Cruz in 2007, four years after the TRC published its final report in 2003. In its decision the Court wrote: The Court recalls that, when complying with its obligation to in- vestigate and, if applicable, punish those responsible for the facts, the State must remove all the de facto and de jure obstacles, that impede the proper investigation of the events, and use all available means to expedite the investigation and the respective proceed- ings in order to avoid a repetition of such serious acts as those examined in the instant case. The State may not invoke any law or provision of domestic law to exempt itself from the obligation to investigate and, if applicable, punish those responsible for the acts against Saúl Cantoral-Huamaní and Consuelo García-Santa Cruz. In particular, the Court recalls that the State may not apply amnesty laws, or provisions relating to prescription, or other provi- sions that exclude responsibility, which prevent the investigation and punishment of those responsible.302 Significantly, in the La Cantuta decision in 2006, the IACtHR reinforced the state’s duty to investigate and conduct criminal trials despite the fact that the Peruvian TRC had thoroughly investigated that case.303 The Court thus does not accept the proposition that a truth commission investigation alone would satisfy the state’s duty to investigate human rights crimes. 6.3 No amnesties for serious human rights violations Currently, there are two categories of international crimes that have become accepted bars to amnesties: enumerated treaty crimes, crimes against humanity and war crimes.304 The Barrios Altos decision, reflecting an already expanding legal framework, suggests a third possible bar to amnesties for crimes that arise out of human rights violations, but which do not necessarily rise to the level of crimes against humanity or war crimes. In this way, a serious violation that did not occur during war and that was not part of a general and systematic pattern of human rights abuses would still trigger a state duty to prosecute, and thus bar immunity measures such as amnesties.305 301 Trumbull, supra note 43, at 301 n.96 (quoting Wilson & Perlin, supra note 300, at 658–59). 302 Cantoral-Huamaní & García-Santa Cruz Case, 2008 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 167, ¶ 190 (July 10, 2007). 303 La Cantuta, 2007 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 162, ¶ 157. 304 See discussion supra notes 144–46. 305 Crimes against humanity are, in essence, human rights violations that are part of a “system- atic and widespread” policy. For a discussion of how crimes against humanity are in fact human rights violations that rise to the level of systematic and widespread, see Tittemore, supra note 107, at 470. Lisa J. Laplante 106 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 In his concurring opinion, Judge Cançado Trindade also raised this issue, insisting that states have an international obligation to protect universally recog- nized, nonderogable rights such as the right to life and personal integrity.306 He argued these rights are protected by the American Convention and “fall in the ambit of jus cogens.”307 He went so far as to say that the adoption and application of amnesty laws is “an international illicit act” because those laws constitute a breach of a state’s responsibilities under the international law of human rights.308 He put it plainly: “It ought to be stated and restated firmly, whenever necessary: in the domain of the International Law of Human Rights, the so-called ‘laws’ of self-amnesty are not truly laws: they are nothing but an aberration, an inadmissi- ble affront to the juridical conscience of humanity.”309 Judge Cançado Trindade offers a novel argument on how to identify the list of crimes to which amnesty should not apply. He gives an historical account of the development and codification of humanitarian law, from the Martens Clause to the Geneva Conventions.310 He contends that “however advanced the codifica- tion of the humanitarian norms might be, such codification can hardly be consi- dered as truly complete,” and goes on to state: The Martens clause […] continues to serve as a warning against the assumption that whatever is not expressly prohibited by the Conventions on International Humanitarian Law could be per- mitted; quite on the contrary, the Martens clause sustains the con- tinuing applicability of the principles of the law of nations (droit des gens), the laws of humanity and the dictates (exigencies) of public conscience […]311 In other words, he directly challenges the idea that only those crimes ex- plicitly codified in international law constitute absolute obligations of states, and thus cannot be subject to amnesty. Judge García Ramírez, with perhaps more prosaic writing, also supported the perspective of his co-justice: The principle, in international human rights law and in the most recent expressions of international criminal law, that the impu- nity of conduct that most gravely violates the essential legal rights protected by both forms of international law is inadmissible, is based on this reasoning. The codification of such conduct and the prosecution and punishment of the perpetrators—and other participants—is an obligation of the State, one that cannot be 306 Barrios Altos Case, 2002 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 75, ¶ 10 (Mar. 14, 2001) (Trindade, J., concurring). For a discussion of nonderogable rights, see Henrard, supra note 78, at 613–16. For comments on the obligation to prosecute for human rights violations, see Carla Edelenbos, Human Rights Violations: A Duty to Prosecute?, 7 Leiden J. Int’l L. 5, 14 (1994). 307 Barrios Altos, 2002 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 75, ¶ 10 (Cançado Trindade, J., concurring). 308 Id. ¶ 11. 309 Id. ¶ 26. 310 Judge Cançado Trindade discusses the Martens Clause introduced at the I Peace Conference of the Hague in 1899, which influenced the later Geneva Conventions. Id. ¶¶ 22–23. 311 Id. ¶¶ 23–24. Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 107EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 avoided by measures such as amnesty, prescription, admitting considerations that exclude incrimination, and others that could lead to the same results and establish the impunity of acts that gravely violate those primordial legal rights. Thus, extrajudicial ex- ecutions, the forced disappearance of persons, genocide, torture, specific crimes against humanity and certain very serious human rights violations must be punished surely and effectively at the national and the international level.312 In sum, these concurring judges propose that human rights violations do not need to be systematic and widespread (and thus crimes against humanity) before amnesties that would interfere with a state’s obligation to investigate, pro- secute, and punish those violations will be prohibited. Subsequent IACtHR decisions have continued to refine and build the jurisprudence on amnesties. These decisions reinforce the interpretation of Barrios Altos as barring amnesties for serious human rights violations.313 For example, in Bulacio the Court does not rely on the argument that the violation occurred as part of a systematic and generalized pattern, and is thus a crime against huma- nity.314 Significantly, the Court frames the duty to investigate, prosecute, and pu- nish as part of reparations, and invokes criminal justice as part of the general right to know the truth—a right belonging as much to the individual petitioners as to Argentine society as a whole. In this way, it folds criminal justice into the idea of restorative justice.315 This interpretation has also been extended by human rights lawyer Brian D. Tittemore, a former staff member in the General Secretariat of the OAS Secretariat for the IACHR, who writes that “the practice and jurispru- dence of the inter-American human rights system has given rise to and reinforced international legal principles and standards governing the obligation of states to ensure individual accountability for serious human rights violations, including those infringements that would constitute crimes under international law.”316 312 Barrios Altos, 2002 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 75, ¶ 13 (García Ramírez, J., concurring) (emphasis added). 313 For example, in Almonacid-Arellano v. Chile, the Court specifically addressed the issue of the prohibition of amnesties for crimes against humanity. Instead of merely referring to the Barrios Altos decision, the Court made a special reading as if to expand the doctrine to extend to crimes against humanities as an obvious extension of human rights violations, since in reality they run along a continuum. Almonacid-Arellano Case, 2007 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 154, ¶ 114 (Sept. 26, 2006) (“States cannot neglect their duty to investigate, identify, and punish those persons responsible for crimes against humanity by enforcing amnesty laws or any other similar domestic provisions. Consequently, crimes against humanity are crimes which cannot be susceptible of amnesty.”). 314 One expert witness described the policy of “razzias” (the vernacular term for the police roundups) as “a more or less systematic policy,” but the Court nowhere else in the opinion made reference to the term “systematic.” Bulacio Case, 2004 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 100, ¶ 53 (Sept. 18, 2003). 315 See id. ¶¶ 110, 112 (citations omitted). 316 Tittemore, supra note 107, at 449. Significantly, Tittemore includes the category of “serious human rights violations” on the list of crimes over which international tribunals (including the ICC and the tribunals in Rwanda and the former Yugoslavia) have jurisdiction. Lisa J. Laplante 108 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 7 State practice: reinforcing the international legal ban to amnesties in domestic courts This final Part explores how subsequent state practice in Latin America may offer additional persuasion as to the broad reach of the Barrios Altos decision. In response to Barrios Altos, many states have annulled their amnesty laws and initiated criminal trials. This is significant, for one, because patterns of state prac- tice ultimately form the basis of customary international law. This phenomenon also supports this Article’s argument that Barrios Altos should be read broadly to prohibit all forms of amnesty for human rights violations. The decisions of domestic courts in Latin America offer persuasive evidence for the broad interpretation of the Barrios Altos case. International law arises not only out of the decisions of international organs, but also the application of tho- se decisions in domestic legal systems.317 Thus, “[o]ne measure of the impact of international law principles, but the most difficult to trace and document, is pre- cisely how well they effectuate this indirect transfer into the national sphere.”318 Others recognize the importance of observing state practice in order to begin car- ving out universal norms. Dugard writes that “it is difficult to identify mandatory rules of international law to govern the conduct of the successor regime. The best one can do is to identify trends that probably qualify as emergent norms. These norms appear from recent state practice.”319 Those who still adamantly argue that amnesties can only be prohibited for treaty crimes point to consistent state practice as evidence of a customary rule of international law in this regard.320 Because states still apply amnesty, they ar- gue, it must be permissible under international law.321 Scharf, a strong proponent of this approach, argues, “Notwithstanding the chimerical conclusions of some scholars, there is scant evidence that a rule prohibiting amnesty or asylum in cases of crimes against humanity has ripened into a compulsory norm of customary international law.”322 He explains that when “widespread practice” begins to con- form to the proclamations of international bodies then, despite a “few instances of departure,” this practice can be called binding customary law.323 317 Roht-Arriaza & Gibson, supra note 31, at 844–45. 318 Id. at 845. 319 Dugard, supra note 60, at 280. 320 See, e.g., Scharf, supra note 103, at 360 (“Customary international law, which is just as bind- ing upon states as treaty law, arises from ‘a general and consistent practice of states followed by them from a sense of legal obligation’ referred to as opinio juris.”). 321 This camp of scholars disagrees with the argument that these countries may in fact be violat- ing international law. See Scharf, supra note 105, at 61 (writing that despite some UN General Assembly resolutions and forceful arguments by legal scholars, “state practice does not yet sup- port the existence of an obligation under international law to refrain from conferring amnesty for crimes against humanity”). For a list of states that have enacted amnesties following episodes of human rights violations, see Trumbull, supra note 43, at 294–97. 322 Scharf, supra note 103, at 360. Scharf makes this argument but omits discussion of the Barrios Altos decision in his article. 323 Michael P. Scharf, Swapping Amnesty for Peace: Was There a Duty to Prosecute International Crimes in Haiti?, 31 Tex. Int’l L.J. 1, 41 (1996); see also Slye, supra note 5, at 175 (citing the increased use of amnesties and thus suggesting state practice). Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 109EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 Heeding the call to monitor state practice, it is significant that state mem- bers of the Inter-American System have now begun to annul the same amnesty laws which initially established the general state practice that suggested they were legally permissible, and they do so relying on the Barrios Altos case. Moreover, these states are now pursuing criminal trials against those responsible for human rights violations in past regimes. In Peru, for instance, the transitional justice experience was dramatically influenced by the Barrios Altos case, as already men- tioned. On April 20, 2002, the Attorney General’s Office of Peru issued a resolu- tion to create a special prosecutor as part of its plan to implement the IACtHR’s decision.324 Soon after, Peru’s Constitutional Court issued seminal decisions that referred to the Barrios Altos decision and served as precedent for all Peruvian courts.325 Indeed, in one of these cases, the court corrected its own jurisprudence issued six years earlier on the issue of amnesty, framing its arguments within the terms of the right to truth.326 Peru’s highest court explained: [I]t falls to the State to prosecute those responsible for crimes against humanity and, where necessary, to adopt restrictive laws to prevent, for example statutes of limitation for crimes against human rights. The application of such laws is conducive to the effectiveness of the legal system and is justified by the prevailing interests of the struggle against impunity. The objective, evidently, is to impede certain mechanisms in the criminal law system, which are applied for the repulsive purpose of securing impunity. This must be prevented and avoided, since it encourages criminals to repeat their behaviors, becomes a breeding ground for vengeance, and corrodes the underlying values of democratic society: truth and justice.327 The opinion, in effect, imbues the transitional justice formula promoted by the TRC with a new legality.328 With the help of the Inter-American System, 324 Resolución de la Fiscalía de la Nación No. 631-2002-MP-FN, Diario Oficial El Peruano No. 221,668 (Apr. 20, 2002) (Peru). The Attorney General issued a follow-up resolution on April 20, 2005, ordering prosecutors in all instances working on cases that were subject to the amnes- ty laws to request the trial or appellate court to enforce the international judgment. Resolución de la Fiscalía de la Nación No. 815-2005-MP-FN, El Peruano (Apr. 20, 2005). 325 Martín Rivas, Constitutional Court, Exp. No. 4587-2004-AA/TC (Nov. 29, 2005) (Peru); Vera Navarrete, Constitutional Court, Exp. No. 2798-04-HC/TC (Dec. 9, 2004) (Peru); Villegas Namuche, Constitutional Court, Exp. No. 2488-2002-HC/TC (Mar. 18 2004) (Peru). 326 Villegas Namuche, Constitutional Court, Exp. No. 2488-2002-HC/TC, ¶¶ 8–20. 327 Id. ¶ 23 (“Asimismo, corresponde al Estado el enjuiciamiento de los responsables de crímenes de lesa humanidad y, si es necesario, la adoptación de normas restrictivas para evitar, por ejem- plo, la prescripción de los delitos que violenten gravemente los derechos humanos. La aplicación de estas normas permite la eficacia del sistema jurídico y se justifica por los intereses prevalentes de la lucha contra la impunidad. El objetivo, evidentemente, es impedir que ciertos mecanismos del ordenamiento penal se apliquen con el fin repulsivo de lograr la impunidad. Ésta debe ser siempre prevenida y evitada, puesto que anima a los criminales a la reiteración de sus conductas, sirve de caldo de cultivo a la venganza y corroe dos valores fundantes de la sociedad democráti- ca: la verdad y la justicia.”) (author’s translation). 328 Significantly, the status of the Barrios Altos decision in national law gained more clarity during the proceedings of the La Cantuta case before the IACtHR. While the Commission and repre- sentatives of the victims argued that the state should take positive steps to annul the amnesty Lisa J. Laplante 110 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 all procedural impediments to pursuing criminal justice as part of the Peruvian transitional justice project were eliminated.329 The TRC’s mandate established its remit to conduct a two-year investigation into the causes and consequences of the armed conflict.330 The Barrios Altos case directly influenced Peru’s decision to include the eventual possibility of criminal investigations and prosecutions in the TRC’s mandate, even if the TRC itself could not conduct such trials. Throughout its two-year investigation, the TRC purposefully conducted its operations in a manner that would support state investigations, even creating a spe- cial criminal investigation unit to prepare cases to present to the state.331 Even befo- re it presented its final report in August 2003, the TRC held a ceremony to transfer for investigation the first case to the Public Ministry to symbolize its commitment to criminal prosecutions. The TRC later transferred an additional forty-three of the most emblematic cases of human rights violations and recommended prompt cri- minal investigations and prosecutions in hundreds of others.332 In addition, its final report included chapters on the most important cases arising out of the twenty-year internal armed conflict, including Barrios Altos333 and La Cantuta.334 Thus, now, some five years after the TRC published its final report in 2003, national public prosecutors across the country have opened hundreds of criminal investigations into alleged extrajudicial killings and disappearances, some of which rose to the le- vel of massacres and all of which occurred during the country’s twenty-year internal armed conflict between state agents and insurgent groups. Meanwhile, many of the criminal investigations into the cases arising out of the friendly settlement reached between Peru and the IACHR were underway as the TRC prepared its final report. The report looked at the incidents at Barrios law, the state responded by saying it was not necessary, naming various other measures taken by the state. See La Cantuta Case, 2007 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 162, ¶ 164 (Nov. 29, 2006). The state argued that “the granting of amnesty has no practical effects in the domestic legal system.” Id. The state, however, added that “in the event the Court held a different view, it should state precisely what such measure would be, since this is not a simple issue concerning domestic law. Under the current Constitution, not only are human rights treaties part of the domestic law, but also any interpretation made by the organs created by such treaties constitute mandatory criteria by which the rights in the country are to be interpreted. Therefore, in the State’s opinion, such legal framework would be sufficient in the current state of affairs.” Id. 329 See generally Eduardo González Cueva, The Peruvian Truth and Reconciliation Commission and the Challenge of Impunity, in Transitional Justice in the Twenty-First Century: Beyond Truth versus Justice 70 (Naomi Roht-Arriaza & Javier Mariezcurrena eds., 2006). By contrast, in South Af- rica, victims could not resort to an international tribunal when they lost their challenge against amnesty laws before the highest national court. See Roht-Arriaza & Gibson, supra note 31, at 856–57 (describing the frustrated attempts of South Afrikaners to contest the amnesty laws). 330 See 1 Comisión de la Verdad y Reconciliacion [Truth & Reconciliation Commission], supra note 162, at 26, available at http://www.cverdad.org.pe/ifinal/pdf/TOMO%20I/INTRODUC- CION.pdf. 331 See González Cueva, supra note 329, at 78–79. 332 During its investigations, the TRC began to present some of its criminal investigations to the Attorney General’s office (author’s personal observations from field work). 333 7 Comisión de la Verdad y Reconciliacion [Truth & Reconciliation Commission], supra note 162, at 475, available at http://www.cverdad.org.pe/ifinal/pdf/TOMO%20VII/Casos%20Ilustra- tivos-UIE/2.45%20BARRIOS%20ALTOS.pdf. 334 Id. at 233, available at http://www.cverdad.org.pe/ifinal/pdf/TOMO%20VII/Casos%20Ilustra- tivos-UIE/2.22.%20LA%20CANTUTA.pdf. Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 111EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 Altos and La Cantuta as part of a general investigation of Colina. Also, on October 16, 2001, the Peruvian Military Council responded to the IACtHR ruling in Bar- rios Altos by declaring “null and void” the Supreme Court judgment issued on June 16, 1995, which extended amnesty to the army officials charged with the Barrios Altos massacre.335 At the same time, the civil courts obtained jurisdiction over these cases.336 As a result, some fifty-six persons were indicted, including a milita- ry general and a top intelligence advisor to Fujimori. Proceedings against Colina agents were also reinitiated in the La Cantuta case, running concurrently with the TRC and resulting in convictions on April 8, 2008.337 In August 2007, the special court for anticorruption, which also handles human rights, opened proceedings against persons involved in La Cantuta, including Luis Augusto Pérez Document, General Hermosa-Ríos, Montesinos, and José Velarde Astete.338 The TRC’s explicit commitment to criminal justice prompted public pro- secutors in the sixteen provinces most affected by the war to open investigations into hundreds of human rights cases.339 For example, a prosecutor in the Andean highlands of Ayacucho, where the greatest brunt of political violence occurred, initiated investigations and prosecutions in some three hundred cases of human rights violations after going into rural communities to interview victims. She na- med former president Alan García among the suspected perpetrators in the case of Accomarca, charging him with genocide (Garcia was president from 1995-1990, and was newly elected in 2006). Thus, beginning in 2005, the provincial and cen- tral criminal courts have issued a handful of significant judgments, some of which include substantial prison sentences for military and police officers. Perhaps most significantly, top leaders—including Fujimori—have been facing trials for crimes arising out of human rights violations. These historical cases are resulting in judi- cial decisions on human rights law which ultimately contribute both to national and international criminal law jurisprudence. 335 La Cantuta Case, 2007 Inter-Am. Ct. H.R. (ser. C) No. 162, ¶ 80(63) (Nov. 29, 2006). The Peruvian officers included: Brigade Army General Juan Rivero-Lazo, Army Colonel Eliseo Pich- ilingue-Guevara, Army Captain José Adolfo Velarde-Astete, Army Lieutenant Aquilino Portella- Núñez, Army Third-Rank Technicians Julio Chuqui-Aguirre, Nelson Rogelio Carbajal-García, Jesús Antonio Sosa-Saavedra, and retired Army Lieutenant Aquilino Portella-Núñez. Id. The October 16, 2001, ruling allowed the perpetrators to return to the procedural status they held before the amnesty laws took effect and allowed the judgment of May 3, 1994, to be served. Id. 336 See Resolución Administrativa No. 170-2004-CE-PJ, Diario Oficial El Peruano (Sept 30, 2004) (Peru). 337 The former head of SIN, General Julio Salazar-Monroe, was sentenced to thirty-five years in prison for his role in the La Cantuta disappearances, and three of his subordinates received fifteen-year sentences for the same offenses. Press Release, Human Rights Watch, Peru: Sala- zar Conviction Step on Road to Justice (Apr. 9, 2008), available at http://www.hrw.org/english/ docs/2008/04/09/peru18489.htm. 338 República del Perú [Republic of Peru], Defensoría del Pueblo [Ombudsman], El Estado frente a las víctimas de la violencia. ¿Hacia dónde vamos en políticas de reparación y justicia? [The State with regard to victims of violence: How far will we go with reparation and justice policy?] 99 n.31 (2007) (Peru), available at http://www.defensoria.gob.pe/inform-defensoriales.php. 339 Coordinadora Nacional de Derechos Humanos [National Coordinator of Human Rights], Informe Anual 2007 [Annual Report 2007], at 22 (2008) (Peru), available at http://www.dhperu. org/documentos/informe/85fa9b_cap1.pdf. Lisa J. Laplante 112 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 One of the most important events in this evolving criminal justice movement was the successful extradition of Fujimori in September 2007, after six years of pro- ceedings, first with Japan and then with Chile. Fujimori faces charges of both cor- ruption and human rights, the latter including the incidents of Barrios Altos and La Cantuta. Fujimori’s trial for the human rights charges began on December 10, 2007. On April 7, 2009, he was found guilty on all human rights charges and sentenced to twenty-five years in prison; Fujimori has declared he will appeal his conviction.340 The Barrios Altos precedent has begun to show its impact in Latin America, beyond just Peru where it applied directly. For example, on June 14, 2005, the Argentine Supreme Court of Justice found the Due Obedience and Full Stop laws were unconstitutional because they violated the country’s international legal obli- gations.341 Part of the Argentine court’s reasoning rested on the Barrios Altos deci- sion, which it interpreted as providing a general bar against all amnesties that pre- vent criminal accountability for serious human rights violations.342 Almost thirty years after the amnesty laws halted criminal justice in Argentina, the influence of the ruling can be seen as national prosecutors open criminal prosecutions against almost three hundred military officers who benefited from earlier amnesty laws.343 The Court relied on international law, including the IACHR’s decision on Argentina’s Full Stop and Full Obedience laws and Barrios Altos, in its decision. The Court specifically interpreted these decisions to apply beyond just self-am- nesty laws, and thus resolved any doubt on the illegality of Argentina’s immunity laws.344 In addition, the Court made reference to the IACHR’s general position that it is “practically irrelevant” that amnesties are enacted by democratic bodies based on the demands of national reconciliation because these laws still violate the American Convention and the duty to prosecute as established in the Velás- quez Rodríquez ruling.345 Significantly, the Argentine justices referred specifically to Judge García Ramírez’s concurring judgment in Barrios Altos in which he argued the decision should be extended to all amnesties despite their possible beneficial effects in reestablishing peace.346 One can also see renewed efforts to pursue criminal justice in Chile, es- pecially in the wake of the Pinochet case which reinvigorated local efforts to as- sure criminal prosecutions for the human rights violations of that country’s dirty war.347 When Pinochet returned to Chile, the Chilean Congress lifted the former leader’s parliamentary immunity to allow criminal proceedings to be initiated 340 Simon Romero, Peru’s Ex-President Convicted of Rights Abuses, N.Y. Times, Apr. 8, 2009, at A6, available at http://www.nytimes.com/2009/04/08/world/americas/08fujimori.html. 341 Corte Suprema de Justicia [CSJN], 14/6/2005, “Julio Héctor Simón,” Colección Oficial de Fallos (2005-328-2056) (Arg.), available at http://www.acnur.org/biblioteca/pdf/3560.pdf. 342 Id. ¶ 24. For a discussion on this issue, see Tittemore, supra note 107, at 449–54 (provid- ing an account of Argentina’s recent judicial decisions on the amnesty laws enacted in its political transition). 343 Canton, supra note 39, at 167. 344 CSJN, 14/6/2005, “Julio Héctor Simón,” Fallos (2005-328-2056), ¶ 25 (Arg.). For a discus- sion of Argentina’s reliance on Barrios Altos, see Márquez Urtubey, supra note 28, at 122. 345 CSJN, 14/6/2005, “Julio Héctor Simón,” Fallos (2005-328-2056), ¶¶ 25–27 (Arg.). 346 Id. ¶ 27. 347 See Evans, supra note 33, at 210. Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 113EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 against him.348 The parliament also presented a bill to annul Chile’s twenty-year- -old amnesty laws to enable criminal proceedings against other suspected human rights violators—the measure was up for a vote at the time of publication.349 In addition, the Supreme Court of Chile ruled on the inapplicability of Chile’s am- nesty laws and statutes of limitations in investigations on forced disappearan- ces.350 Chile, along with Spain and South Africa, has also renewed efforts to bring perpetrators to justice, providing that “despite explicit efforts to leave the past behind, the contentious issue of human rights refuses to remain buried.”351 These renewed campaigns for criminal justice suggest that those who poin- ted to these same countries as examples “that truth could substitute for justice” to argue that state practice supported amnesties, overlooked the resilience of the “thirst for justice.”352 Indeed, local victims eventually began to force a sea change in state behavior and put into question some of the once accepted tenets of the truth v. justice debate through their diligent use of international legal recourse. Essentially, the maxim appears today to be truth and then later justice. Justice may be delayed but nonetheless the principle of criminal justice remains in the equation.353 Moreover, it seems a new stage in the transitional justice field is mo- ving away from the truth v. justice debate, which poses the options in binary terms of choosing between trials or truth commissions (i.e., either/or), and instead ex- panding to the view that transitional justice encompasses both options (i.e., and/ also). Indeed, Peru’s clear deviance from the truth commission model set in South Africa could divert the international trend, making the South African experience suddenly an isolated exception.354 The more current trend is to see countries opting for both truth commis- sions and criminal prosecutions.355 For example, upon revoking a blanket amnesty offered in peace negotiations, Sierra Leone eventually annulled that law and for- 348 Id. 349 Agenda de Derechos Humanos para el Bicentenario [Human Rights Agenda for the Bicenten- nial], Comisión del Constitución del Senado Aprueba Derogación de Amnistía [Senate Consti- tutional Commission Approves Amnesty Derogation] (Dec. 18, 2008), athttp://adhb.wordpress. com/2008/12/18/comision-del-constitucion-del-senado-aprueba-derogacion-de-amnistia/ (Chile). 350 Miguel Angel Sandoval Rodríguez Case, Corte Suprema de Chile (Nov. 17, 2004), available at http://www.derechos.org/nizkor/chile/doc/krassnoff.html (referring to Chilean Decree Law No. 2191 of 1978). 351 Evans, supra note 33, at 208; see also David A. Crocker, Reckoning with Past Wrongs: A Normative Framework, 13 Ethics & Int’l Aff. 43, 53 (1999); Margaret Popkin & Nehal Bhuta, Latin American Amnesties in Comparative Perspective: Can the Past be Buried?, 13 Ethics & Int’l Aff. 99, 111 (1999). 352 Roht-Arriaza, supra note 2, at 313. 353 See Marguerite Feitlowitz, A Lexicon of Terror: Argentina and the Legacies of Torture 193 (1998) (discussing Argentina’s “Scilingo Effect” of confessions coming two decades after junta rule ended). 354 See Jenkins, supra note 61, at 46 (noting South Africa’s exceptional experience based on the exchange of amnesty for confessions); Suzannah Linton, Cambodia, East Timor and Sierra Leone: Experiments in International Justice, 12 Crim. L.F. 185 (2001) (discussing the experiences of coun- tries opting for criminal trials). 355 Carsten Stahn, Accommodating Individual Criminal Responsibility and National Reconciliation: The UN Truth Commission for East Timor, 95 Am. J. Int’l L. 952, 954 (2001) (writing on the develop- ment of truth commissions into a “justice-supportive machinery”). Lisa J. Laplante 114 EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 med a Special Court at the same time it created a Truth Commission in 2002.356 Now, almost two decades after the truth v. justice debate gained momentum, con- sensus suggests that truth commissions and criminal trials are “mutually reinfor- cing and complementary,” rather than options which create tensions, tradeoffs, and dilemmas. 357 Certainly the new global context, aided by judicial pronouncements like Barrios Altos, greatly influences the international community’s attitude towards amnesties, which also influences the pressure on national leaders to pursue crimi- nal justice.358 In this vein, political scientist Elin Skaar found that in thirty Latin American and African countries that underwent transition after the mid-1970s, the government’s human rights policy rested largely on the “relative strength” of the public’s demand for truth and justice balanced with the outgoing regime’s demand for amnesty and impunity.359 8 Conclusion The IACtHR offered the international community a holding in Barrios Altos that if read broadly could cause monumental changes in transitional justice sche- mes. Yet, despite my inclination to refute narrow readings of the Inter-American decision, I at the same time must acknowledge one significant factor that could nevertheless continue to limit the reach of Barrios Altos. In particular, the steadily growing framework of international law has created new dilemmas and concerns regarding the lack of uniformity in a system that has no overarching court or legis- lature to unify laws and practice. Indeed, the IACtHR is a regional tribunal, whose holding technically is only binding on OAS members, and then only to those who have signed the American Convention. Thus, we are left with the question whether the Barrios Altos precedent sig- nifies a new evolution in the general field of international law for all countries, or alternatively only for the region of Latin America. Is it a watershed in combating international impunity, or just one more example of the type of fragmentation in international criminal law that Gerhard Hafner views as the “erratic blocks and elements” of an “‘unorganized system’ full of intra-systematic tensions, contra- dictions and frictions”?360 It will be important to watch whether the Barrios Altos decision begins to serve as persuasive authority in other regions and settings in order to assess its full impact. 356 See Schabas, supra note 99, at 157–61. The Special Court went on further to test the valid- ity of the amnesty laws finding that a state may not create amnesties to protect offenders from prosecution for crimes that amount to an international crime subject to international jurisdic- tion. Id. at 161. 357 Leebaw, supra note 40, at 103. 358 See generally Naomi Roht-Arriaza, Special Problems of a Duty to Prosecute: Derogation, Amnesties, Statutes of Limitation, and Superior Orders, in Impunity and Human Rights in International Law and Practice, supra note 25, at 57. 359 Elin Skaar, Truth Commissions, Trials—or Nothing? Policy Options in Democratic Transitions, 20 Third World. Q. 1109, 1124 (1999). 360 Gerhard Hafner, Pros and Cons Ensuing from Fragmentation of International Law, 25 Mich. J. Int’l L. 849, 850 (2004). Outlawing amnesty: the return of criminal justice ... 115EJJL Chapecó, v. 13, n. 3, p. 59-116, Edição Especial 2012 Regardless of its reach, the implications of the outlawing of amnesties in transitional justice settings, even if contained in Latin America, generate new questions in the field. One recent line of inquiry looks at how international cri- minal law is being “nationalized” and again how this creates issues of “fragmenta- tion” in terms of the substance and application of international legal norms. For instance, in holding human rights trials while respecting the principles of legality, which law do states apply? In the case of Peru, which only recently codified ex- trajudicial execution close to the end of Fujimori’s regime in 1998, it is applying common criminal codes of homicide. How does this choice of law contribute or undermine the developing norms of international criminal law, or does it even matter? Will evolving state practice and jurisprudence result in difficult contra- dictions and inconsistencies, or will it slowly evolve into a uniform system? Finally, if the trend points toward inclusion of national criminal trials in transitional justice settings, what will be the implications for the now broader goals of these schemes in terms of restorative justice? Will national reconciliation be undermined? Will national trials perhaps be compromised by inexperienced, weak, or corrupt courts, and will political realities only increase victim-survivors’ distrust and disappointment? Or alternatively, will a new legality inspire more creative ways of upholding the principle of criminal justice while carving out ex- ceptions such as plea bargaining and prosecutorial discretion? These are only a few of the questions that arise when contemplating a new phase in the development of transitional justice. While the binary nature of the truth v. justice debate perhaps simplified the conversation by providing two options, we now enter a more complex and nuanced territory that may test the social and political limits of a new legality that limits the possibility of choice. Data da submissão: 10 de maio de 2012 Avaliado em: 31 de outubro de 2012 (Avaliador A) Aceito em: 9 de novembro de 2012 work_dinirwmov5fmrgfzwskwuif7ie ---- Memory, Justice and the Public Record Memory, Justice and the Public Record Gudmund Valderhaug Introduction In March and April 2008, while I was preparing this paper for the Ethics of Memory Construction conference in Ann Arbor, Bergens Tidende (the major newspaper in Western Norway) published a series of articles on women that had been victimised after the liberation in May 1945 because they had fraternised with German soldiers during the Nazi occupation. The series triggered a passionate debate in the press and in other media. Some voices, provoked by the articles’ viewpoints, claimed that, even though the public reactions against these girls had been exaggerated and regrettable, there should be no doubt that many of them had acted contrary to national interests during the occupation. However, the great majority of debaters asserted that the girls in general had been innocent victims of an unjust revenge, and that their only “crime” was that they had fallen in love with men in a Wehrmacht uniform. The scale and passion of this debate indicates that the treatment of these women still represents a traumatic memory for many Norwegians. The paper that I was preparing was meant to deal with the fate of these women’s children, the Norwegian “war children”. Women who had fraternised with German soldiers became targets for popular revenge in all European countries that had been occupied by Nazi Germany, but the case of the Norwegian war children is remarkably special. One incident might serve to illustrate this: In July 1945, Norwegian authorities made contact with several European countries, asking how these countries intended to solve their “war child problem”. Apparently, most of these countries didn’t understand the question; the war children were not considered to be a pressing issue anywhere else than in Norway (Borgersrud 2005, 124-125). The Unwanted Children A report in the German daily Frankfurter Rundschau on 4 May 2002 tells the story of a war child. She was born in 1943; her mother was Norwegian, her father a German soldier. Shortly after her birth, she was taken to a Lebensborn children’s home near Oslo. As a one year old she was moved to another Lebensborn home near Bremen in Germany. After Hitler’s surrender, she was found there by Norwegian representatives. They sent her to Sweden, where she was adopted by a Swedish couple and given a new identity as the daughter of a woman who had died in a Nazi concentration camp. After the liberation in May 1945, government officials were set to deport the war children 1 from Norway. Eventually, these plans failed; only one group of some 30 children was actually deported to Sweden in summer 1945, and this woman was one of these (Borgersrud 2005, 73-92). She grew up believing she was a survivor from the Holocaust. She didn’t learn about her true identity until 1996, when she approached the Swedish National Archives to find out which camp she came from and who mother had been. “You don’t come from a concentration camp,” the archivist said, “you come from Norway”. Norwegian historian Lars Borgersrud’s explores the development of official Norwegian politics concerning the war children, and analyses the motivations for these politics, in his significant study “Vi ville ikke ha dem” (2005). Borgersrud suggests that the deportation plans were built on mainly two conditions. Firstly, deportation of children as a means to solve social problems had been an established procedure in many countries for several decades, especially in Great Britain (Coldrey 1993). Secondly, the war children were regarded as inferior citizens. This was a result of the continuous impact of eugenic thinking on politics and medical science since the 1920s, which regarded biological or genetic factors as decisive for an individual’s societal position (Simonsen and Ericsson 2004). Indeed, in 1945 one leading Norwegian medical expert warned that the war children could represent a future threat to the mental health of the nation. His line of argument went like this: Only a mentally underdeveloped girl would want to fraternise with the enemy, and 1 According to the official statistic record there were born 8364 children with Norwegian mothers and German father between 1941 and 1946. Historians generally agree that these records are not complete. only an equally underdeveloped German soldier would be content with a girl like that; consequently the offspring of such breeding most probably would be underdeveloped children (Olsen 2004, 103). This state politics obviously had broad public support. An important reason for this was the public condemnation of the mothers of the war children. In Norway, as elsewhere in Europe, women who had intimate relations with Germans during the occupation became targets for popular revenge in May 1945. The so-called “German girls” were considered to be guilty of a double betrayal, both nationally and sexually. However, the great majority of these women did neither sympathise with Nazism nor betray their country, and contrarily to what seems to have been general belief at the time, only a small percentage were prostitutes (Jørgensen, 43-44). It has been suggested that this condemnation was sexually fixated; the dominant patriarchal ideology of that time considered female sexuality to be uncontrollable and a possible threat to society. Thus, popular opinion regarded sexual collaboration as the greatest treason of all, and more visible than other kinds of collaboration because of its ultimate evidence: the children. And even though the condemnation and revenge wasn’t aimed directly at the children, it still affected them; they were the living proof of their mothers’ sins . Partly because of this, most of the war children were also subject to various degrees of bullying and social exclusion in their neighbourhoods and at schools. Due to the victimisation and ostracism of their mothers, a large number of war children grew up in orphanages, with their grandparents or other relatives, or were adopted (Borgersrud 2005, Simonsen 2001). Lars Borgersrud’s research has shown that a number of state bureaucrats spent quite a bit of energy on this matter during 1945; there were even informal negotiations with Swedish officials to arrange adoption of children in Sweden. There was but one problem: most of the War Children were Norwegian citizens, which made deportation of them illegal. This left the bureaucrats with two options: Either to get their mothers’ consent to send the children abroad, or to do something with their citizenship. This was precisely what was done in August 1945, when a special decree deprived women that had married a German after the invasion on 9 April 1940 of their Norwegian citizenship. Most of these women were deported to Germany, some of them together with their children. In October 1945, the Norwegian government officially abandoned future deportation plans. But even after this, some bureaucrats continued their efforts to get rid of the children. When an Australian immigration commission visited Oslo in November that year, they were literally offered 9 000 war children across the table. But the Australians did not accept; “Half- German” kids were neither wanted in the British Empire in 1945. After the deportation plans were abandoned, the war children were still discriminated by state politics. A great number of them were excluded from the national family allowance system, which was introduced in 1947 as the first major social reform in the Norwegian welfare state program. This system gave all Norwegian children a monthly benefit from the state. But a considerable part of the war children were in practice excluded from this system: Those who had lost their Norwegian citizenships because their mothers had married a German during the war, and those who didn’t live with their mothers (Borgersrud 2005, 365). Another example of public discrimination was the question of getting child support from the German fathers. For political reasons, Norwegian authorities did not want the unmarried mothers to be in touch with their children’s fathers, and all legal proceedings to establish paternity – about 6 000 cases – were halted in 1946. When these cases were re-opened in 1950, only a small portion of the mothers re- established their claims and less than 500 fathers ended up paying (Borgersrud 2005, 363-64). As a result of this economic discrimination from the state, the majority of the war children grew up under poorer economic conditions than other children. The Construction of the War Children The war children had nothing in common except their fathers’ nationality. A German- Norwegian child was not a war child if its mixed national parentage was unknown to others. As a group, they were a social construction. This construction was founded on the concievable knowledge of each individual’s existence, which was made possible by the registration of the children and their parents in the Lebensborn records. The existence of this archive, I will suggest, was an important condition for the particular Norwegian history of the war children. Lebensborn – “the source of life” – was an organisation established by SS Reichfürer Heinrich Himmler, initially to run maternity homes for unmarried pregnant German women of the “Aryan race”. After the outbreak of WW2, its activities were expanded to include services for widows and children of fallen SS soldiers, and for children of German soldiers and native mothers in occupied territories. In Norway, Lebensborn had the highest high level of activity outside Germany, running at least 9 homes for children and mothers. Norway was the only occupied country with a central Lebensborn headquarters. One reason for this was that the Nazi leaders considered Norwegians to be racially acceptable; because of this, sexual relationships between German soldiers and Norwegian women were positively tolerated, if not encouraged. More important, the children that such relationships might produce might be racially healthy and worthy of Lebensborn care (Olsen 2004). In his article “The Archive and the German Nation”, Peter Fritzsche has shown how archives became an important resource for the implementation of Nazi racial politics: “This required not only the mobilization of existing records for political ends but the creation of new records that would recognise the biological categories that the Nazis held to be so consequential. As the definition of the political became more biological, so did the official archive” (Fritzsche 2005, 196). Fritzsche quotes the director of the Bavarian archives, who in 1936 established that “[t]here is no practice of racial politics without the mobilisation of source documents, which indicate the origin and development of a race and a people… There is no race politics without archives, without archivists” (ibid). The records in the Lebensborn Norwegian HQ were also created for this purpose. If a woman became pregnant with a German soldier, she and the assumed father individually had to answer special questionnaires about themselves and their relationship, and information about the woman’s health condition and race was collected and registered. When the woman was in the last half of her pregnancy, she could move to a Lebensborn home and stay there until six weeks after the child had been born. If she didn’t want to keep the child, Lebensborn would arrange adoption or keep it in one of their children homes. If the mother kept the child she was entitled to a rather generous support from Lebensborn, which in turn requested that she kept them informed about the child’s health and development. If the couple wanted to get married, Lebensborn could help them to sort out the paperwork (Jørgensen, 22-23). Evidence of all such matters were registered and filed in the Lebensborn archive. After the German surrender, this archive gave Norwegian authorities access to detailed information about some 8 500 war children and their mothers. Without these records, the Norwegian authorities would not have had access to any accumulated national register of war children, as Norwegian birth registration at this time was decentralised and no national registers were kept. Norway was the only occupied country where a central Lebensborn archive had been created. I will suggest that this archive became critical for the unique Norwegian construction of the war children as a societal group, and for the subsequent development of a special politics towards the war children. The existence of this archive made it possible to identify the individual war children, to treat them as a specific social group. In other occupied countries, where such an archive didn’t exist, this was not possible. In the early 1950s, the war children ceased to be a national political issue. Their background gradually became unmentionable, a societal taboo invoking shame, and their German traces were hidden from public memory. In 1953, a municipal childcare officer in Oslo wrote: “In the main, all these children with foreign soldier fathers have been included in the population of this country in an excellent way” (Simonsen 2001). However, most War Children would probably disagree with this statement. One of them later wrote, “[a]s a war child one had no fellowship. Not even one’s own family did speak about these terrible things. In my reality as a war child there was simply no one to share these terrible things with” (Borgersrud 2005, 9). In local communities, schools, institutions, and even in their families, a war child’s troubles became individualised, and disconnected from the group’s common troubled past. The Struggle for Justice Then, in the early 1980s, things changed. Post-war issues that had been hidden for almost 40 years were brought into the public domain by novelists, journalists, historians and others. “German girls” and war children came forward with their stories. In 1986, new legislation gave adopted children the right to know who their biological parents were. Consequently, war children approached the archives where the adoption files were kept and became aware of the Lebensborn archive. During the late 1980s and the 1990s more than 1 500 individual war children approached the National Archives alone to find information about their biological family (Olsen 2004, 95). Such things also occurred in other countries that had been under German occupation. But once again Norway became special: the major public issue concerning the war children was not to be the individuals’ search for their biological roots, but their struggle for justice, for restitution for the discrimination and harassment that they had experienced as a result of the state’s politics. In 1986 the Norwegian Association of War Children was established and the organised struggle for justice began. I will not give a broad account of the war children’s struggles. Suffice it to say that they got some results; in 1998 the Norwegian government commissioned the Norwegian Research Council to organise a three-year research project on the war children’s childhood, and in his New Year speech 01.01.2000 the Norwegian prime minister publicly apologised for the state’s treatment of the children. In 2003, a Governmental White Paper (St.meld. 44 2003-04) proposed a special reparation system for war children, which was approved by the Norwegian parliament in 2005. This system, which lasted through 2006 and 2007, allowed individuals who had experienced infringement and persecution in neighbourhoods, at school or by public officials to claim compensation for this. The size of this compensation was to be made dependent on the evidence that each individual might bring forth. If an individual could document “grave suffering, loss or damage”, she or he could get between NOK 20.000 and NOK 200.000. When such documentation couldn't be found, a compensation of maximum NOK 20.000 could be given dependent on individual statements that made it credible that the person in question had been subject to harassment (St.meld. 44 2003-04). The result of the reparation system is as follows, according to official reports: The total number of war children who applied for compensation in 2006-07 were 2 025. By the end of 2007, 1097 cases had been handled. In 2007, 59% of the war children who received compensation got NOK 20 000 or less. In 2006, this percentage was as high as 77% (Justissekretariatene 2007). In other words, a majority of the applicants has not been able to bring forth any “documentation” of their troubles as war children. This illustrates the main problem with the compensation system: The white Paper made the individual compensations dependent on the “documentation” that each war child might produce, but what was meant by the notion “documentation” was not defined. However, in comparable cases “documentation” is usually used synonymously with public records. The Silent Archives The public records documenting the war children may be divided into three parts, according to their provenance. Firstly, the Lebensborn records, which document the war children’s lives until May 1945. After 1945, some of these records were used in legal proceedings to establish paternity and ended up in regional state agencies. Secondly, records created by the central Norwegian government in the conduct of national policies after WWII. In the main, these records document the development of national politics towards the war children as a group. Lars Borgersrud, whose study uncovers the motives and processes behind the state’s war child policies after WW2, states: “The state has created good records, which often are easily accessible. But, of course, they express the authorities’ versions. When the state oppresses, the researcher will be exposed to the oppressor’s understanding of reality” (Borgersrud 2005, 10). In this particular case, I would suggest, Borgersrud’s statement is rather an understatement. Finally, the records created by the local municipal bodies that were responsible for primary schools, public childcare, children's homes and social services. These records should contain evidence of the individual war child as a school child or a child care client. However, these municipal records are incomplete and defective. The main reason for this is poor record creation in the municipal sector, due to the public administration regime of the time. Before the introduction of the legislation on public administration and freedom of information in 1970, public case handling processes were insufficiently documented, especially in smaller organisations like schools, childcare administrations and children’s homes. The records that actually were created were not accessible for clients, so unlike today, the public record- making processes were largely beyond public control (Valderhaug 2004). Furthermore, a considerable part of the records that were created do not exist today. The municipal sector did have a very weak archival tradition; Norwegian municipal archival institutions were established in the 1970s or later. Consequently records may have been lost or destroyed by accident. Lack of archival control may have made it easier for people with something to hide to get rid of archival evidence. Even today, about one-third of Norwegian municipalities are without archival institutions. Consequently, a great part of the records that still may exist are unprocessed, unlisted and unavailable for use. What then, could be said about the private records documenting the war children’s pasts? They must exist, of course; like other individuals the war children have created personal records: diaries, letters, and photographs, and their families, relatives, mothers, grandparents and friends will have created relevant records. However, such personal records are not considered to have the same evidential qualities as organisational records. But, as far as I know, no archival institutions have collected such records. This privileging of public records originates from the assumption that the state and other public bodies are neutral expressions of society, and that the records created by such entities will be impartial by-products of administration. But, as Verne Harris notes, “[r]ecords always already express relations of power and invite the exercise of power (Harris, 241). In this particular case these power relations should be unusually obvious; the records in question were created by the very same public bodies that discriminated against the war children and neglected their needs, and they created the records to justify exactly the same actions. Consequently, the war children's own voices are not present in the Norwegian archival heritage. Towards an Archival Justice The case of the war children confronts the archivist with a number of challenges. Some of these involve the concrete relationships between the archivist and the war child coming to an archives to find records that may or may not exist, others relate to the ethics and praxis of social memory construction. All these challenges are, I will suggest, fundamentally about justice. On the one hand, they are about our relation to individuals seeking some kind of individual justice, a compensation for a troubled past. On the other hand, they address our obligations towards such marginalised groups on the collective level, in their quest for a historical – and archival – justice. The archivist’s role in the documentation of personal rights is to be an archivist. It is not our job to pretend to be lawyers or social workers. It is not for us to decide whether the documentation we are able to find will be sufficient to get reparation or not. It is neither our role to engage in client counselling. We cannot grant people justice. But we can use our knowledge to locate whatever documentation there is to be found, so that the individuals may have their cases tried at the proper authorities. Our role, then, is to supply documentation and put this into the societal and administrative context. And this role is indeed difficult and challenging. As an intermediary between the public and the records themselves, the archivist occupies a position of power in relation to the user. She controls access to the information the user needs and she can – to a certain degree – decide how much of her time and knowledge she will share with him. So how should archivists react when approached by people asking for records documenting injustice, when they know that these records may or may not exist? I will suggest that such cases leave the archivist with two options: She may handle the enquiry in a formally correct manner, just like we handle any other enquiry we get. This will include introducing the user to the finding aids and helping him identifying the records in question, without providing any special service, thus following the recommendations in article 6 in the ICA Code of Ethics offering “impartial advice to all”. If the records exist and can be identified, they will be obtained from the repositories and made available for the user. If they can't be identified, the story usually ends here. But it doesn’t have to end here. There is another option; the archivist may use her archival expertise to uncover to uncover the conditions of record creation in the given period: What administrative procedures may have been used? What kind of information might have been archived in the first place? Is it probable that any of the records might have been lost? Could there be found better information at other archives? And: Is it possible to reconstruct any of the missing documentation from the few traces that may be found? For an archivist, used to handling enquiries from researchers, students and family historians, from people more or less belonging to our professional family, choosing this second option implies encountering the stranger. Individuals that approach the archives to find documentation of injustice committed against themselves, are very often strangers to the archives. They have never been to an archives before; they don’t know how to use our finding aids; they may not even understand the record’s bureaucratic rhetoric. They represent a new kind of users, signifying something new, something unknown, something strange – and sometimes even frightening. They approach us with their demands for justice, with their angst and their hopes, with their wants and their desires; they are coming to change their lives. The archives are strange to them; they know little about what may be found there, but they know that the archives are part of the same public system that some years ago neglected or mistreated them. And they may even be even strangers in the archives, because their lives are poorly documented – and sometimes totally absent – in the records. Today, such requests represent a large and increasing part of the public enquiries in Norwegian archives, especially in the municipal sector. They come from individuals who claim they were abused in children’s homes, individuals who didn’t get the education they we entitled to, people who in some way or another were excluded from the social welfare system that were built in the post-war era, and they come from war children. One archival institution that has recent and important experiences from such matters, is the Bergen City Archives. During the last decade, the City Archives has handled some hundred requests for documentation from former children's homes inmates. Due to the state of the surviving records, tracing one person’s childcare history could often be a time-consuming business. To be able to identify where the records concerning one person might be found, it sometimes even was necessary to sit down and interview the individual to hear his or her personal story. In some cases, these memories were the keys that opened the archives and made it possible to find the relevant documentation (Valderhaug 2005). These experiences suggest that equal rights to archival information can’t be reduced to equal rights to access. It must also include equal rights to benefit from the information in the archives, and a prerequisite for achieving this is to offer unequal and differential services. People with little or no experience with archives will have a greater need for guidance than the experienced reading room visitor. And it is commonly people looking for documentation of personal rights that have the greatest need for assistance from the archivist. The development of such services will obviously take time and resources from other important tasks at an archival institution. Still, there are strong arguments that doing this should be an obligation for an archives serving a democratic society. Jacques Derrida’s states that “effective democratisation can always be measured by this essential criterion: the participation in and access to the archive, its constitution and its interpretation” (Derrida 1996, 4). A living democracy depends on every citizen's right to access, understand and use public information, including current and archival records, for their own individual – or collective – purposes. This right must form an integral part of what might be called an archival justice. However, an archival justice must also include the right to participate in the creation of the archive. For archivists, this raises at least two important issues. A comprehensive discussion of these is beyond the scope of this article, so I will merely indicate the problems. The first issue concerns the archivist’s engagement with current record creation processes in public administration. During the last two decades archivists have spent quite a lot of energy on developing standards and guidelines for electronic recordkeeping, to ensure the enduring authenticity and reliability of electronic records. There has been less attention given to another, but equally important issue: expanding democratic control of the records creation process. In democratic countries, public administration is generally subject to regulations requiring transparency and freedom of information and that decisions should be supported by relevant written documentation. Still, regardless of legislation, public records will be created for certain purposes, reflecting the dominant social and cultural values, and thus reproducing existing power relations. However, the legal structures of transparency and freedom of information might be used to counteract such reproduction. I will suggest that public control of the public record might be crucial to avoid the creation of biased and defective records documenting societal processes, including the marginalised groups of our time: migrant workers, asylum seekers, Muslims, drug addicts, etc. Should archivists – and records managers – use this legislation to promote the creation of “just” records? How could this eventually be done? Is the development of guidelines for democratic control of public recordkeeping a possible answer? The second issue is about the creation of another memory of the past. This might be done by bringing existing records into the public domain, or by collecting or creating new records. Kåre Olsen, archivist at the Norwegian National Archives and responsible for handling the war children's enquiries in the 1990s, was the first researcher to publish a scholarly study on the war children and their mothers (Olsen 1998). He did this for two main reasons: “little had been written on themes like war children... I also found that war children who applied to the National Archives often knew very little of the history of the war children” (Olsen 2004, 107). Thus, Olsen broke the scholarly silence on this issue, and his work was obviously an important cause when the Government commissioned the Norwegian Research Council to start their research project on the war children. Now, in 2009, the war children's reparation system is history. A number of individual war children have received economic compensation for “grave suffering, loss or damage” and some might argue that justice now has been done (as if a destroyed childhood ever can be compensated with money). Still, I will argue, as long as the war children’s own stories are absent from the archives, justice will be superficial. In a couple of decades the most of the war children will have passed away, and their stories may once again pass into oblivion. Only the defective public records will survive. As long as the war children’s own stories remain untold and unrecognised by society, justice will be superficial. The emergence of real justice will be dependent on an archival intervention to collect the war children’s own stories. This implies inviting war children to record their own stories, to archive these stories and make them available for use; thus giving the silenced voices the chance to supplement the existing archival heritage and thereby contribute to the construction of a more democratic and inclusive societal memory. Sources Borgersrud, L (2005): Vi ville ikke ha dem. Scandinavian Academic Press, Oslo. Derrida, J (1996): Archive Fever. University of Chicago Press. Coldrey, B (1993): Good British Stock. Child and Youth Migration to Australia 1901- 83. Identified on the World Wide Web 13 March 2008 at http://www.naa.gov.au/naaresources/Publications/research_guides/guides/childmig/introduction.htm. Fritzsche, P (2005): The Archive and the German Nation, in Antoinette Burton (ed.): Archive Stories. Duke University Press, London/Durham 2005. Harris, V (2007): Archives and Justice. Society of American Archivists, Chicago. International Council on Archives – ICA (1996): Code of Ethics. Identified on the World Wide Web 13 March 2008 at http://www.ica.org/sites/default/files/Ethics-EN.pdf Jørgensen, H (2006): Norske kvinner og tyske soldater. Master thesis, University of Tromsø. Olsen, K (1998): Krigens barn. De norske krigsbarna og deres mødre. Aschehoug, Oslo Olsen, K (2004): Women and Children in the Front Line: The ”Jerry Girls” of Norway and their Children, in: Comma 2004.1 (International Council of Archives) Simonsen, E (2001): Stjålen barndom, 2001. Identified on the World Wide Web 23 March 2008 at http://www.hf.uio.no/ikos/forskning/forskningsprosjekter/vokse_opp/seminarer/10_2001/simonsen.html Simonsen, E and Ericsson, K (2004): Krigbarn i fredstid – sosialpolitiske og profesjonelle føringer i synet på norsk-tyske krigsbarn 1945-47. University of Oslo, Department of Criminology and Sociology of Law, K-series 1/2004. St.meld. 44 (2003-04) Erstatningsordning for krigsbarn og erstatningsordninger for romanifolk/tatere og eldre utdanningsskadelidende samer og kvener. Identified on the World Wide Web 23 September 2006 at http://www.regjeringen.no/nb/dep/jd/dok/regpubl/stmeld/20032004/Stmeld-nr-44-2003-2004- .html?id=198295&epslanguage=NO Valderhaug, G (2003): Recordkeeping in Local Government in Norway 1950–2000. In Archival Science Vol. 3, No. 2. Valderhaug, G (2005): Memory, Archives and Justice. Identified on the World Wide Web 17 October 2007 at http://depotdrengen.wordpress.com Valderhaug, G (2007): The Good Archivist. Identified on the World Wide Web 17 October 2007 at http://depotdrengen.wordpress.com http://www.naa.gov.au/naaresources/Publications/research_guides/guides/childmig/introduction.htm http://www.ica.org/sites/default/files/Ethics-EN.pdf http://www.hf.uio.no/ikos/forskning/forskningsprosjekter/vokse_opp/seminarer/10_2001/simonsen.html http://www.regjeringen.no/nb/dep/jd/dok/regpubl/stmeld/20032004/Stmeld-nr-44-2003-2004-.html?id=198295&epslanguage=NO http://www.regjeringen.no/nb/dep/jd/dok/regpubl/stmeld/20032004/Stmeld-nr-44-2003-2004-.html?id=198295&epslanguage=NO http://depotdrengen.wordpress.com/ http://depotdrengen.wordpress.com/ Årsrapport fra Justissekretariatene 2007. Identified on the World Wide Web 23 October 2008 at http://www.justissekretariatene.no/upload/Om%20Justissekretariatene/Årsrapport%2 02007.pdf http://www.justissekretariatene.no/upload/Om%20Justissekretariatene/Årsrapport%202007.pdf http://www.justissekretariatene.no/upload/Om%20Justissekretariatene/Årsrapport%202007.pdf work_belcuinjffejvnenqovt6xvs2a ---- Theories of Social en Economic Justice Th eor ies o f So cia l an d E co no m ic J us tic e Theories of Social and Economic Justice T h eories of S ocial an d E con om ic Ju stice A J van d er W alt Edited by AJ van der Walt T he bulk of the contributions in Theories of Social and Economic Justice originated in a research project initiated by the Stellenbosch Institute for Advanced Study (STIAS) in 2002. STIAS hosted a workshop in July 2004 in which researchers from Law, Economics, Theology and Sociology participated, and some of the contributions at the workshop were subsequently reworked into chapters for this book. In addition, colleagues, both in South Africa and abroad, who had not participated in the workshop but whose recently published work on social and economic justice fitted in with the project extremely well, gave permission to re-publish their articles in the book. The book is based on the idea that the attainment of greater social and economic justice, specifically in the South African context, is strongly influenced by the implications and the coherence of various theories of social and economic justice. Furthermore, it is argued that the promotion and protection of social and economic justice need to be approached from different theoretical perspectives when considering different practical circumstances, contexts and dilemmas. One theoretical size simply does not fit all, as far as social and economic justice is concerned. The range of theoretical approaches represented in this book – legal, economic, theological and sociological – is testimony to the truly cross- and multi-disciplinary nature of the contributions. Apart from leading South African scholars in Law, Economics, Theology and Sociology, four contributions from American academics are included: Professors Gregory Alexander (Cornell Law School), William Forbath (University of Texas), Lucy Williams (Northeastern University), and Ross Zucker (Lander College). AJ van der Walt is professor in the Faculty of Law at Stellenbosch University and author of Constitutional Property Clauses: A Comparative Analysis (1999) and Constitutional Property Law (2005). He is also a co-editor, with H Botha and J van der Walt, of Rights and Democracy in a Transformative Constitution (2004, AFRICAN SUN MeDIA). THEORIES finaal Q5 2/8/05 9:15 Page 1 A Research Project of the Stellenbosch Institute for Advanced Study The Stellenbosch Institute for Advanced Study (STIAS) is a high-level research institution dedicated to keep Africa at the forefront of inter- national scientific developments. It facilitates innovative and inter- disciplinary research on issues that are of special relevance to the continent. It does so by inviting leading researchers from all over the world to work in close interaction with their counterparts from Africa. By including younger researchers in its projects, it contributes to the development of a next generation of scholars. Website: http://academic.sun.ac.za/stias/ Theories of Social and Economic Justice edited by AJ VAN DER WALT Professor, Faculty of Law, Stellenbosch University SUN PRESS is a division of AFRICAN SUN MeDIA, Stellenbosch University’s publishing division. SUN PRESS publishes academic, professional and reference works in electronic and print format. This publi- cation may be downloaded or ordered directly from www.sun-e-shop.co.za. Published by SUN PRESS, a division of AFRICAN SUN MeDIA, Victoria Street, Stellenbosch 7600, South Africa www.africansunmedia.co.za All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any electronic, photographic or mechanical means, including photocopying and recording on record, tape or laser disk, on microfilm, via the Internet, by e-mail, or by any other information storage and retrieval system, without prior writ- ten permission by the publisher. First edition 2005 ISBN 1-919980-82-2 Cover design by Laura Oliver Typesetting by Felini Studio Set in 10 on 12.5 pt Sabon Printed and bound by US Printers, Ryneveld street, Stellenbosch 7600 Copyright permissions William Forbath ‘A not so Simple Justice: Frank Michelman on Social Rights, 1969 – Present‘ first appeared in (2004) 39 Tulsa Law Review 597-638. © W Forbath and Tulsa Law Review. Reprinted here (with minor editorial changes) with the kind permission of W Forbath and Tulsa Law Review. Sandra Liebenberg ‘The Value of Human Dignity in Interpreting Socio-Economic Rights‘ first appeared in (2005) 21 South African Journal on Human Rights 1-31. © S Liebenberg and Juta & Co, publishers of SAJHR. Reprinted here (with minor editorial changes) with the kind permission of S Liebenberg, I Currie (editor of SAJHR) and Juta & Co. Charles Ngwena ‘The Historical Development of the Modern South African Health-Care System: From Privilege to Egalitarianism‘ first appeared in (2004) 37 De Jure 290-312. © C Ngwena. Reprinted here (with minor authorial and editorial changes) with the kind permission of C Ngwena and De Jure, the editor of De Jure and Lexis-Nexis Butterworths. Theunis Roux ‘Pro-Poor Court, Anti-Poor Outcomes: Explaining the Performance of the South African Land Claims Court‘ first appeared in (2004) 20 South African Journal on Human Rights 511-543. © T Roux and Juta & Co, publishers of SAJHR. Reprinted here (with minor editorial changes) with the kind permission of T Roux, I Currie (editor of SAJHR) and Juta & Co. Lucy Williams ‘Beyond Labour Law’s Parochialism: A Re-Envisioning of the Discourse of Distribution’ first appeared in J Conaghan, RM Fischl & K Klare (eds) Labour Law in an Era of Globalization: Transformative Practices and Possibilities (2002) Oxford University Press 93-114. © L Williams and Oxford University Press. Reprinted here (with minor editorial changes) with the kind permission of L Williams, J Conaghan, RM Fischl and K Klare and Oxford University Press. Contents PREFACE 1 GREGORY S ALEXANDER 6 Socio-Economic Rights in American Perspective: The Tradition of Anti-Paternalism in American Constitutional Thought DANIE BRAND 17 The ‘Politics of Need Interpretation’ and the Adjudication of Socio-Economic Rights Claims in South Africa STAN A DU PLESSIS 37 New Tools for the Constitutional Bench FANIE DU TOIT 56 Social Justice and Theological Method WILLIAM FORBATH 72 A not so Simple Justice: Frank Michelman on Social Rights, 1969 – Present DERIK GELDERBLOM 108 The Just Community: Emile Durkheim on Liberalism and Society NICO N KOOPMAN 128 Theology and the Fulfilment of Social and Economic Rights: Some Theoretical Considerations SANDRA LIEBENBERG 141 The Value of Human Dignity in Interpreting Socio-Economic Rights ELSABE LOOTS 168 The Fiscal Implications of Social and Economic Justice: An Overview of the Changing Theoretical Framework CHARLES NGWENA 179 The Historical Development of the Modern South African Health-Care System: From Privilege to Egalitarianism THEUNIS ROUX 199 Pro-Poor Court, Anti-Poor Outcomes: Explaining the Performance of the South African Land Claims Court DIRKIE J SMIT 225 On Social and Economic Justice in South Africa Today: A Theological Perspective on Theoretical Paradigms LUCY A WILLIAMS 239 Beyond Labour Law’s Parochialism: A Re-Envisioning of the Discourse of Redistribution ROSS ZUCKER 256 Opening the Door to More Equality BIBLIOGRAPHY 291 CASES 309 LEGISLATION AND POLICY DOCUMENTS 312 INDEX 314 Preface The bulk of the contributions that make up this book originated in a research project initiated by the Stellenbosch Institute for Advanced Study (STIAS) in 2002. The Director of the Institute, Bernard Lategan, asked me whether I would be interested in running a research project with STIAS; I proposed a project on Theories of Social and Economic Justice, which was accepted; and the result was that STIAS hosted a workshop in July 2004 in which researchers from Law, Economics, Theology and Sociology participated. One distinguished participant was a STIAS Research Fellow at the time, Gregory S Alexander (Cornell Law School).1 The contributions at the workshop were of such a standard and the debate so interesting that everybody agreed that it would be useful to publish some of the papers resulting from the presentations. Participants were therefore invited to submit papers for publication. Johan van der Walt (University of Johannesburg) and Dr Tessa Marcus (National Research Foundation), both of whom attended the workshop, helped me decide which of the presentations were suitable for publication and made suggestions on possible amendments and revisions. The end result was a group of very interesting papers dealing with various theories of social and eco- nomic justice. However, because of the fairly rigorous review process the selected contributions were just not quite substantial enough for a full-scale publication and I had to either supplement the selected papers or abandon the publication project. One or two of the participants published extended versions of their workshop presentations or related work in peer-reviewed journals and agreed to these articles being re-published here.2 To flesh out the intended publication I also approached a number of colleagues, both in South Africa and abroad, who had not participat- ed in the workshop but whose recently published work on social and economic justice fitted in with the project extremely well, and I asked them for permission to re-publish their articles and essays together with the ones selected from the workshop. They all graciously agreed, and the result is the book you have in your hands now.3 The idea for the STIAS project on Theories of Social and Economic Justice had its origin in an article I had written in 2002 for a collection of South African essays in honour of US schol- ar Frank I Michelman.4 In that article, I developed the thought that the attainment of greater social and economic justice, specifically in the South African context, was strongly influenced 1 Prof Alexander’s work on social and economic justice includes GS Alexander ‘The Concept of Property in Private and Constitutional Law: The Ideology of the Scientific Turn in Legal Analysis’ (1982) 82 Columbia LR 1545-1599; GS Alexander Commodity & Propriety: Competing Visions of Property in American Legal Thought 1776-1970 (1997). 2 Sandra Liebenberg ‘The Value of Human Dignity in Interpreting Socio-Economic Rights‘ first appeared in (2005) 21 SAJHR 1-31; Theunis Roux ‘Pro-Poor Court, Anti-Poor Outcomes: Explaining the Performance of the South African Land Claims Court‘ first appeared in (2004) 20 SAJHR 511-543. 3 William Forbath ‘A not so Simple Justice: Frank Michelman on Social Rights, 1969 – Present‘ first appeared in (2004) 39 Tulsa Law Review 597-638; Charles Ngwena ‘The Historical Development of the Modern South African Health-Care System: From Privilege to Egalitarianism‘ first appeared in (2004) 37 De Jure 290-312; Lucy Williams ‘Beyond Labour Law’s Parochialism: A Re-Envisioning of the Discourse of Distribution’ first appeared in J Conaghan, RM Fischl & K Klare (eds) Labour Law in an Era of Globalization: Transformative Practices and Possibilities (2002) Oxford University Press 93-114. Ross Zucker kindly agreed to write a sub- stantially new contribution for this volume, based on the theoretical worked that underlies his recently pub- lished book Democratic Distributive Justice (2002). 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E by the implications and the coherence of various theories of social and economic justice. One of my central hypotheses in that article was borrowed from Frank Michelman, namely that my approach would be what Michelman described as ‘provisional adoption, as inchoate legal doc- trine, of a theory of social justice.’5 In other words, I accepted that theory does make a differ- ence on the struggle for greater social and economic justice, but nevertheless argued that the best approach was not to develop a single, coherent and all-encompassing grand theory but rather to uncover the strengths and the weaknesses of several theoretical approaches for differ- ent contexts and circumstances.6 In doing so I was aware of the danger of facile eclecticism and tried to avoid it – the fact that several theoretical approaches could have different benefits in various contexts does not mean that they are all relatively or equally useful or valid; in fact, sev- eral theories are subjected to strong criticism in the article. The ‘new property’ theories based on Charles Reich’s work,7 for instance, are subjected to a critique that implies that these theo- ries are not suitable for arguments in favour of state provision of access to social and econom- ic benefits.8 Equally strong criticism is leveled at equality-based theories, partly relying on a cri- tique developed by Michelman.9 On the other hand, however, equality-based theories have proven to be particularly useful and strong when attacking state provision of social and eco- nomic support on the basis of non-participation, lack of access or unfair denial and termina- tion; just as the property-based theories are very useful when protecting already vested and acquired benefits from amendment or termination. In short, the article concluded that the pro- motion and protection of social and economic justice need to be approached from different the- oretical perspectives when considering different practical circumstances, contexts and dilem- mas. One theoretical size simply does not fit all, as far as social and economic justice is con- cerned. In the process of developing and making this argument I concentrated quite strongly on the central distinction between rights-based and needs-based theories of social and economic jus- tice, partly because of Michelman’s pivotal role in emphasizing the distinction and the impor- tance of the often ignored needs-based arguments.10 The theoretical arguments on either side of this divide have both weaknesses and strengths, which underlines the central finding that a variety of even seemingly contradictory theoretical approaches could offer useful insights when developing strategies for the promotion and protection of social and economic justice. Rights talk has serious shortcomings and has quite rightly been criticized very harshly; needs talk poses considerable theoretical and moral problems that detract from its intuitive appeal; but never- theless the experience of the impoverished and the marginalised in post-apartheid South Africa has shown convincingly that both kinds of rhetoric may have their place in strategic thinking about social and economic transformation. When faced with the stark reality of the utterly and 4 The book was published as H Botha, A van der Walt & J van der Walt (eds) Rights and Democracy in a Transformative Constitution (2003). My essay, entitled ‘A South African Reading of Frank Michelman’s Theory on Social Justice’, appeared at 163-211. It was subsequently re-published in (2004) 19 SA Public Law 253-307. I refer to the original pagination in Botha, van der Walt & van der Walt here. 5 Van der Walt (note 4 above) at 180, citing FI Michelman ‘The Supreme Court 1968 Term – Foreword: On Protecting the Poor through the Fourteenth Amendment’ (1969) 83 Harvard LR 7 at 10. 6 In van der Walt (note 4 above) at 204ff I described this process as ‘twisting rope’. 7 C Reich ‘The New Property’ (1964) 73 Yale LJ 733; C Reich ‘Individual Rights and Social Welfare: The Emerging Legal Issues’ (1965) 74 Yale LJ 1245. 8 Van der Walt (note 4 above) at 168. 9 Van der Walt (note 4 above) at 174. hopelessly destitute, those who have lost even whatever access to rudimentary shelter and safe- ty they had through natural disaster or social upheaval, there is just no place for a hard-nosed approach based on rights talk, and a different attitude is required. To their credit, the South African courts have shown a growing awareness of this need for different approaches in differ- ent circumstances, and they have been particularly successful in developing a context-sensitive and weakness-aware approach to the position of those who cannot claim anything within the parameters of a strictly rights-based discourse.11 However, in another context it is equally valid to abandon the softer approach of needs talk and resort to the harder, more self-confident rhet- oric of rights when that is the best way of protecting rights already acquired.12 The article had three theoretically interesting implications that informed the STIAS project. Firstly, I concluded that ‘theory matters’; in other words, theory makes a difference in the prac- tical, legal and political struggle around social and economic justice. The struggle for social and economic justice was not theory-innocent, theory-neutral or theory-agnostic; in fact, it was very directly and clearly informed and influenced by theoretical assumptions, even when those assumptions were taken for granted and never questioned, discussed or even clearly articulat- ed. Whenever a particular instance of legislative drafting, policy formulation, administrative action or judicial decision-making avoided or ignored theoretical arguments or approaches completely, the result was not that it was theory-neutral but rather that it simply accepted and confirmed the ‘normality assumption’,13 that set of theoretical assumptions accepted without thinking by the majority of a particular interpretive community at a certain time. The second implication was, in the tone of a hypothesis, that theory had restraining as well as energizing effects on the promotion of social and economic justice, because the more or less automatic reliance of the ‘normality assumption’ or default position would usually resist change and affirm the status quo. Moreover, lack of theoretical development could result in a kind of ‘theory drag’ in the sense that practical political development could sometimes outstrip theo- retical thinking, creating a vacuum of nonexistent theoretical explanation, justification and inspiration that could hold development back even when the political will to promote it is strong. This effect was clearly visible in the South African situation ever since the promulgation of the new democratic constitutions in 1993 and 1996: political development easily outpaced academic efforts to produce and develop suitable, useful theoretical work that could serve as inspiration and reflective material for policy making, and ever since academics have more or less been doing their utmost to catch up with – rather than prompt, inspire or challenge – pol- icy making and legislative processes. The third conclusion was already alluded to earlier: theoretical interest for and the effect of theory on the promotion of social and economic development reflect a wide range of different kinds and levels of theoretical thinking, ranging from legal doctrine through political philoso- phy to critical theory, from due process-based theories of political organization, division of powers and judicial law-making to social theories of individualism, community and the ethics Preface 3 10 Van der Walt (note 4 above) at 196-204. In his contribution to this book Forbath analyses Michelman’s con- tribution and arguments in depth. 11 Particularly in Government of the Republic of South Africa and Others v Grootboom and Others 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC); but see further in Port Elizabeth Municipality v Various Occupiers 2005 (1) SA 217 (CC). 12 E g in Nhlabati and Others v Fick 2003 (7) BCLR 806 (LCC). 13 A phrase coined by Rosemary Coombe ‘”Same as it Ever Was”: Rethinking the Politics of Legal Interpretation’ 1989 McGill LJ 603-652. 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E of care. Legal theory, political theory, social theory, economic theory, theological thinking and many other fields of theoretical endeavour could possibly cast useful light on the dynamics that either promote or inhibit the promotion of social and economic justice. The project therefore had to be a cross- or multi-disciplinary one. The question was: are there any benefits to be had from discussing social and economic justice from the perspective of these theoretical hypothe- ses in different disciplines? Is it worthwhile to investigate the notion that theoretical assump- tions and paradigms affect the promotion of social and economic justice; or the idea that the- ory drag could inhibit social and economic development? The participants in the STIAS workshop took on the challenge to discuss the ideas that ‘the- ory matters’ and of ‘theory drag’ and developed them in the fields of economic theory, social philosophy, theological thinking and legal theory. The range of theoretical approaches repre- sented in this book exemplifies the success of their efforts, and the fact that it made more sense to arrange the contributions alphabetically rather than thematically is testimony to the truly cross- and multi-disciplinary nature of the contributions. The most obvious way of arranging the contributions, namely according to broad subject (law, economics, theology) was preclud- ed by the fact that economists and theologians involved themselves deeply in legal theory (Stan du Plessis, Dirkie Smit, Fanie du Toit), just like lawyers, theologians and sociologists involved themselves deeply in economic theory (Ross Zucker, Derik Gelderblom and Fanie du Toit). The range of theoretical approaches from which the importance and the potential effect of theory on social and economic justice are analysed in the contributions to this book is surpris- ingly wide, although there is a perhaps predictably strong interest in the conflicts between social and communitarian theories and individualist, liberal theoretical approaches (Smit, Koopman, Liebenberg, Brand, Roux, Gelderblom, Ngwena, Forbath, Alexander, Williams). Several con- tributors investigate different versions of what could be described as a dialogic or discursive theory of rights (Nico Koopman, Danie Brand), while others discuss different institutional the- ories of rights (Stan du Plessis, Theunis Roux, Ross Zucker). One of the fairly general conclu- sions that could be drawn from the contributions as a whole is that liberal, individualist theo- ries could tend to inhibit the promotion of social and economic justice in so far as these theo- ries rely strongly on individual rights, whereas social and economic justice at least sometimes requires state-sponsored actions that are not premised on the existence of such rights (Liebenberg, Roux, Brand, Ngwena). These general conclusions are supported by more detailed and contextual analyses of the promotion of social and economic justice in very specific areas such as labour (Williams), land reform (Roux), and health services (Ngwena), from which more general arguments about social and economic justice follow. The value of these analyses is enhanced by the comparative theoretical contributions from US scholars (Alexander, Forbath, Williams and Zucker) and by historical perspectives (Alexander, Forbath, Ngwena). In sum, these contributions constitute a valuable source of theoretical insight and argument about social and economic justice, particularly about the role of theory in either promoting or inhibiting the advancement of justice. A number of people contributed to the success of the STIAS workshop and the resulting book. Bernard Lategan, the director of STIAS, provided continuing financial, intellectual and institutional support for the whole project. Johan van der Walt and Tessa Marcus contributed intellectual insight in and rigour to the evaluation and selection of presentations. Gerhard du Toit provided enthusiastic assistance with the editing of contributions and he also compiled the bibliography and index. All the participants in the STIAS workshop, both those who present- ed papers and the discussants, helped to generate valuable discussion and intellectual exchange from a variety of disciplines. The participants who submitted contributions to this book assist- ed in taking the discussion further and in developing the ideas and insights into something that can form the basis for continuing debate. Contributors who agreed to write new work or to re- publish their earlier work in the book made it possible to produce a more extensive and wide- ranging collection of readings. Journals, editors and publishers who agreed to re-publication graciously allowed us to produce this wider collection of contributions. STIAS and Sun Press generously agreed to assist in publishing what is an extremely interesting but in many respects probably not very profitable book. I would like to extend my warm and heartfelt gratitude to them all. André van der Walt Stellenbosch May 2005 Preface 5 Socio-Economic Rights in American Perspective: The Tradition of Anti-Paternalism in American Constitutional Thought G R E G O RY S A L E X A N D E R Robert Noll Professor of Law, Cornell University, Ithaca, NY I Introduction As many constitutional law scholars have noted, with respect to socio-economic rights, American constitutional law is an outlier. While many, perhaps even most, of the world’s con- stitutions recognize at least some socio-economic rights, either textually or through judicial inter- pretations, the US Constitution does not. Individuals have no basis under the American consti- tution for asserting positive claims against the state for the provision of even the barest of neces- sities. Nor is there any basis for constitutional socio-economic rights even as aspirational goals. Why is this the case? Why has American constitutional law never recognized socio-econom- ic interests as rights that entitle individuals to substantive protection, even aspirationally? Professor Cass Sunstein has argued that the best explanation focuses on a particular historical moment when a change in the membership of the US Supreme Court undermined the only opportunity that has existed for the Court to recognize constitutional socio-economic rights.1 In making this argument, Sunstein rejects several other possible explanations, including expla- nations that look to American legal traditions and culture. In this brief essay, I shall suggest that while Sunstein’s self-styled ‘Legal Realist’ explanation is correct as far as it goes, it is incomplete. Sunstein too quickly rejects legal culture and tradition as the key to understanding why American constitutional jurisprudence has historically not given sub- stantive protection to socio-economic interests. A deeper look at the traditions of American legal jurisprudence reveals that the continual presence of a distinctive social vision in constitutional thought that is fundamentally at odds with the idea of constitutional socio-economic rights. This social vision is that of anti-paternalism. Anti-paternalism has both framed the way in which American judges view socio-economic interests and created a strong presumption against any full- scale recognition of such interests as substantively-protectable constitutional rights throughout American constitutional history, though such rights certainly do exist as a statutory matter. The explanation for America’s failure to recognize socio-economic rights at a constitutional level results, I will argue, from a combination of two factors: the legal-political culture of anti-paternalism and the institutional character of constitutional rights in the American political and legal sphere. 1 CR Sunstein The Second Bill of Rights: FDR’s Unfinished Revolution and Why We Need It More than Ever (2004). In focusing on the culture of anti-paternalism, I am not proposing a monist theory. Anti-pater- nalism has not been the exclusive social vision throughout American history. Another social vision has also been available in American constitutional thought, and this alternative vision might have been exploited to support the recognition of constitutional socio-economic rights as compatible with the traditions of American constitutionalism. This is the social vision of civic republicanism. While civic republican ideas have not been ascendant in American constitution- al jurisprudence since the 18th century, their presence has been felt at particular moments and may yet be felt again. Civic republicanism, however, is a recessive gene in American’s constitu- tional genetic order. It seems highly unlikely to have the kind of strength necessary to generate the constitutional mutation that would yield a new species of individual rights in the American system. Moreover, there are substantive aspects of civic republicanism, particularly its historic hierarchical and exclusionary characteristics, that make it a weak candidate for supporting sub- stantive socio-economic rights as a constitutional matter. Before explaining why American constitutional law has never recognized socio-economic interests as basic rights, I need first to establish that in fact they have not, at least not overtly or robustly. I will then turn to the question of explanation and briefly sketch the anti-paternal- ist social vision that has made the idea of socio-economic interests as substantive constitution- al rights seem uncongenial, if not anathema to the American legal mind. II Socio-Economic Interests In American Constitutional Jurisprudence The appropriate starting place in any study of the status of socio-economic rights in American constitutional law is the familiar distinction in liberal thought between positive and negative rights. Positive rights, orthodox liberal thought tells us, impose affirmative obligations on the state to act on behalf of the individual. They compel the state to reach into its pocket to make provi- sion for certain individual needs. They remove from the realm of governmental discretionary judg- ment the decision about whether to ensure that individual citizens enjoy the basic material condi- tions necessary for both civic participation and personal self-development. Negative rights, by contrast, restrain the state from acting, rather than requiring, as positive rights do, its affirmative action on behalf of individuals. They are ‘checks,’ that is, means of protecting individuals from governmental actions that unduly impinge on a sacred sphere of personal autonomy. Classical lib- eral legalism considers negative rights as real rights and positive rights as unpalatable pretenders. This distinction between negative and positive rights is the appropriate starting place for under- standing the place of socio-economic interests in American constitutionalism because American constitutional thought invariably labels socio-economic rights as positive rights and, as such, ersatz rights. The commonplace understanding in the United States is that constitutional rights are exclusively negative rights. Judge Richard Posner has pithily expressed what is in most American constitutional law circles regarded as bedrock truth: the American Constitution ‘is a charter of negative rather than positive liberties.’2 Posner further explains, ‘The men who wrote the Bill of Rights were not concerned that Government might do too little for the people, but that it might do too much to them.’ What Posner is telling us is that there is no constitutional right to socio- economic benefits,3 nor will such a right ever exist in the American constitutional scheme. Socio-Economic Rights in American Perspective 7 2 Jackson v City of Joliet 715 F 2d 1200, 1203 (7th Cir) cert denied 465 US 1049 (1983). 3 DP Currie ‘Positive and Negative Constitutional Rights’ (1986) 53 Univ of Chicago LR at 864, 864. 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E Posner’s assessment is misleading in several respects. Consider first his unexamined reliance on the conventional distinction between negative and positive rights. The distinction between the two is less categorical than first meets the eye. A central insight of the American Legal Realists was that so-called negative rights are in fact interventionist in character. The exercise of such rights require government assistance, most conspicuously through enforcement. Indeed, Bentham pointed out that property rights would not exist in the absence of state power. The dependence of negative rights on affirmative state action makes the distinction between posi- tive and negative rights much less clear than Posner and classical liberal theory recognize. A second reason why Posner’s dismissal of positive rights from the pantheon of American constitutional rights is inaccurate is the fact that although American constitutional rights tra- ditionally have been negative in nature, positive rights are not entirely unknown in American constitutional jurisprudence.4 Many American state constitutions contain affirmative guaran- tees of specific socio-economic interests, such as education.5 The New Hampshire Constitution of 1784 even constitutionalized the Lockean social compact by conferring on every citizen ‘the right to be protected . . . in the enjoyment of his life, liberty, and property.’6 More important perhaps, the American Supreme Court, while generally rebuffing efforts to recognize positive constitutional rights, has recognized positive rights in a few instances. In 1956, the Court held that the equal protection clause requires states to provide trial transcripts (or their equivalent) to poor people appealing their criminal convictions.7 A decade later, the Court held that state poll taxes violate the Constitution. The effect of that ruling was that states must provide the vote free of charge despite the fact that this imposes costs on the state.8 To some extent, then, it is inaccurate to say that the American Constitution does not recognize any positive socio-economic rights or rights that require the state to reach into its pocket. Posner might object that the recognition of rights such as these does not prove very much with respect to socio-economic interests. In these cases the Court recognized positive rights only when the meaningful exercise of some independent and fundamental aspect of citizenship, such as the right to vote or to prove criminal innocence, required the provision of economic benefits by the state. That is not the case with respect to socio-economic rights. It is worth pausing for a moment on just what we mean when we speak of ‘socio-econom- ic rights.’ Liberals (classical liberals) consider socio-economic rights to be ‘second-generation rights,’ with the first generation being classical liberal negative rights. In modern times, they were first introduced into the American political and legal lexicon in a serious way in President Franklin D Roosevelt’s famous Second Bill of Rights address to Congress.9 Roosevelt’s Second Bill of Rights, which, along with the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, inspired the social rights provisions of many modern constitutions,10 included not only welfare rights but work- related rights as well. Thus, among the rights Roosevelt specified were ‘[t]he right to earn enough to provide adequate food and clothing and recreation’ and ‘[t]he right to a useful and remunerative job in the industries or shops or factories or mines of the Nation.’ Roosevelt 4 See DP Currie The Constitution of the Federal Republic of Germany (1994) at 14. 5 See eg Ill Const Art X § 1. 6 NH Const Pt I Art 12 (1784). 7 Griffin v Illinois 351 US 12 (1956). 8 Harper v Virginia Board of Elections 383 US 663 (1966). 9 FD Roosevelt ‘Objectives of the Administration’ (June 8, 1934) in The Public Papers and Addresses of Franklin D Roosevelt (1938) vol 3 at 291-92. 10 WE Forbath ‘Not So Simple Justice: Frank Michelman on Social Rights 1969-Present’ (2004) 39 Tulsa LR 597 at 598 fn 7. See reprint in this volume at 72. grouped these rights together with welfare rights like ‘[t]he right of every family to a decent home,’ ‘the right to adequate medical care and the opportunity to achieve and enjoy good health,’ and the right to ‘social security.’ Since Roosevelt’s time, most of the attention in the US has been directed to welfare rights rather than work rights (though recently some progressive scholars have refocused attention on work rights11). Welfare rights are the sorts of rights that most proponents of constitutional socio-economic rights have in mind, and it is these sorts of rights that, as Judge Posner correctly suggests, have never been recognized in American consti- tutional law.12 The most sustained effort to gain constitutional recognition of welfare rights in the United States occurred during the late 1960s and early 1970s, the height of the War-on-Poverty era. The type of rights that activist lawyers urged the Court to recognize were welfare rights. The legal theory that many of these lawyers used was the so-called ‘New Property’ theory proposed by Yale law professor Charles Reich in a famous 1964 article by that name. Reich argued that what he called government ‘largesse,’ a broad collection of government benefits including both welfare transfer payments and employment-related licenses, should be constitutionally protect- ed as property since in the modern welfare state they serve the same function as traditional forms of property. Welfare-rights lawyers gained some Supreme Court victories in the 1970s, but these victories do not contradict my claim that American constitutional jurisprudence has never recognized socio-economic interests as substantively-protected rights. While the ‘New Property’ cases do represent the highwater mark of the most serious effort to introduce socio- economic interests into the realm of constitutionally-protected individual rights, they fell far short of the goal of entrenching personal economic welfare as substantive constitutional right. In its broadest ruling on the ‘New Property’ theory, the Supreme Court in Goldberg v Kelly held that the Fourteenth Amendment’s due process clause requires that a welfare recipient be given an evidentiary hearing prior to termination of benefits. Citing Reich’s article, Justice Brennan wrote, ‘It may be realistic today to regard welfare entitlements as more like ‘property’ than a ‘gratuity.’ Much of the existing wealth in this country takes the form of rights that do not fall within traditional common-law forms of property.’ Brennan’s opinion, however, said nothing to indicate that the Court was prepared to recognize a substantive right to welfare. Although so distinguished an academic commentator as Frank Michelman viewed the opinion as signaling a willingness to consider that a right to subsistence may legitimately be found in some provision of the Constitution, there was really nothing in the Court’s opinion to suggest that the state was under a constitutional obligation to create any welfare program.13 Any pos- sibility that the Court might so expand on its tenuous acceptance of Charles Reich’s theory was soon dashed when the Court, in Dandridge v Williams held that a state family-assistance law was valid even though its cap on maximum payments left many families living at state-recog- nized poverty levels. And just two year later, the Court, in upholding a state’s summary evic- tion procedure, baldly stated that the ‘Constitution does not provide judicial remedies for every social and economic ill.’ The Constitution, said the Court, does not provide a ‘guarantee of access to dwellings of a particular quality.’ However slightly the door to judicial recognition of some kind of substantive constitutional right of welfare might have been opened by Goldberg v Kelly, it was emphatically closed in these later cases. Since that time, the door has remained shut and securely locked. Socio-Economic Rights in American Perspective 9 11 See ibid. 12 See Currie (note 3 above) at 866. 13 See Currie (note 3 above) at 872. 1 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E III Sunstein’s Explanation Why has this been our history? Why have American courts refused to read into the Constitution any sort of substantive right to even the barest of welfare needs? Professor Cass Sunstein has examined four possible explanations. Three are theories that other writers have offered to explain why socio-economic interests are not protected as constitutional rights in the American legal system. Rejecting all three of these, Sunstein proposes a fourth theory. It is worth a brief look at the first three because all have surface plausibility. The first of these theories is a chronological theory. This theory points to the fact that the American Constitution is an 18th century document. At that time, constitutional rights, which were still in their infancy, simply weren’t thought of as including social and economic guar- antees. Created against the backdrop of monarchical governments, classical constitutional rights were barriers against abuses of state power. This was certainly the English tradition, and that tradition was the template for all constitutional bills of rights created during the classical era. The difficulty with this explanation, Sunstein points out, is the American Constitution has hardly been a static document. It has been formally amended, sometimes in quite dramatic ways. Yet at no point in American history, not even the late 1960s or early 70s, has there ever been serious discussion of amending the Constitution to include substantive welfare rights. Moreover, the original meaning of the American Constitution has also been changed, some- times quite sharply, through the process of judicial interpretation, yet never for the purpose of introducing socio-economic rights. Chronology alone cannot explain this fact. The second theory that Sunstein considers and rejects is pragmatic and institutional. The basic argument is that American constitutional rights have been pragmatic rights, rights that are capable of being judicially enforced. They are not simply expressive of our deepest values. They may well have expressive content, but they are not solely expressive. The nearly-universal view of constitutional rights among American lawyers, scholars, and courts is that they are tools for implementing actual legal, political, and social change. Aspirational rights have had no place in our constitutional history, unlike that of many countries whose constitutions have recognized socio-economic rights. This strongly pragmatic understanding of constitutional rights is closely related to the role of courts as interpreters of the Constitution. Judicial review has long been the central preoc- cupation in American constitutional thought and practice, and there is a widely-held view that a substantive constitutional right to social welfare cannot easily coexist with judicial review. Courts, many constitutionalists believe, are simply unable to enforce a constitutional provi- sion mandating health care, housing, or even food. Such a constitutional provision would end up being an empty promise, mocking the very idea of what a constitutional right is supposed to be. Sunstein perceptively points out the flaws in this explanation as well. For one thing, while the Federal Constitution lacks a constitutional right to social welfare, many state constitutions do not. The experience with those provision has been mixed, but at least in some of the states courts have been somewhat willing to enforce their social and economic rights.14 Moreover, as Sunstein points out, the fact that courts would be unable completely to enforce a constitution- al guarantee regarding housing or employment would hardly be unique in our constitutional 14 See eg Tucker v Toia 371 NE 2d 449 (NY 1977). experience. The same is true of our existing, negative rights. As he says, ‘[T]he prohibition on unreasonable searches and seizures [is] violated every day.’15 What courts could do is to prompt legislatures to create programs aimed at fulfilling the constitutional guarantee or adequate housing or health care and to exercise at least a modicum of supervision over those programs. American federal courts have undertaken such supervisory functions in the context of other constitutional rights. While their performance in this capacity has perhaps been less than ideal, there is no evidence that the fact that they have fallen short of completely implementing the rel- evant constitutional right has undermined public confidence in the meaningfulness of the right itself. So, this pragmatic explanation, like the chronological explanation, is at best incomplete. The third explanation that Sunstein examines is one that I think he dismisses too quickly. I will briefly mention it at this point and come back to it later to offer a variation on it. The explanation is cultural in nature. It is the familiar story of American exceptionalism. Specifically, the theory is that the absence of social welfare rights from the list of American con- stitutional rights can be traced to the absence of socialism in our political history. Since social- ism has never been a significant force in American political ideology, the theory goes, it is hard- ly surprising that there has been a major effort to inject what are, after all, essentially socialist- style rights in the Federal Constitution. Responding to this theory, Sunstein does not doubt that socialism has never played a major role in American politics, nor does he question the connec- tion between social welfare rights and socialist forces in countries that have recognized consti- tutional socio-economic rights. He argues instead that a strong socialist movement is neither a necessary nor a sufficient condition for social and economic rights.16 There are example of countries with strong socialist movements but no constitutional socio-economic rights (Sunstein cites Canada and Israel), and he says one can easily imagine that a country without a socialist past might be inspired to give constitutional recognition to social welfare rights. After all, President Roosevelt, who despite some of his contemporary detractors was no socialist, did call on Congress to adopt his Second Bill of Rights as a legislative matter. Why not as a constitu- tional matter? The answer, Sunstein asserts, must lie elsewhere. He finds the answer in his fourth theory, a theory that he labels ‘Realist,’ in a gesture to the American Legal Realists who contended that constitutional law, like all law, is a matter of con- crete human actions and human personalities.17 Here, in a nutshell, is Sunstein’s theory: …The crucial development was [sic] the election of President Nixon in 1968 and his four appointments to the [Supreme] Court: Warren Burger in 1969, Harry Blackmun in 1970, and Lewis Powell and William Rehnquist in 1972. These appointees produced a stunning series of decisions, issued in amazingly rapid succession, which … made it clear that for the most part, social and economic rights have no constitutional status…18 The idea is that as of 1970, the Supreme Court was on the verge of reading some form of a right to social welfare into the Constitution through the Fourteenth Amendment due process clause or the equal protection clause but that the appointment of four moderate-to-conservative new justices to the Court closed the door to that opportunity. Had Hubert Humphrey, rather than Socio-Economic Rights in American Perspective 11 15 Sunstein (note 1 above) at 144. 16 Ibid p 136-137. 17 This was hardly the emphasis of all, or even most, of the American Legal Realists. The one Realist whom this description best fits was J Frank Law and the Modern Mind (1930). 18 Sunstein (note 1 above) 163. 1 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E Richard Nixon, been elected president in 1968, things would have turned out differently and the United States would have become another member of the club of countries whose constitu- tions recognize socio-economic rights. While others have offered the same theory,19 it is less compelling than meets the eye. The claim that 1970, the year of Goldberg v Kelly, was the golden-but-lost moment for a constitu- tional right to welfare relies on a more expansive reading of that case that is warranted. Scholars like Sunstein who read Goldberg as signaling the pre-Nixon Supreme Court’s willing- ness to recognize a substantive right to welfare into the Constitution emphasize dicta in the Court’s opinion that is promising but misleading. The Court stated, for example, ‘From its founding the Nation’s basic commitment has been to foster the dignity and well-being of all per- sons within its borders. We have come to recognize that forces not within the control of the poor contribute to their poverty.’20 The Court went on to say …Welfare, by meeting the basic needs of subsistence, can help bring within the reach of the poor the same opportunities that are available to others to participate mean- ingfully in the life of the community. . . . Public assistance, then, is not mere charity, but a means to [quoting here from the Preamble to the US Constitution] ‘promote the general Welfare, and secure the Blessings of Liberty to ourselves and our Posterity…21 The real meaning of the Court’s high-flown rhetoric is grasped when we put it in the context of the legal issue before the Court. That issue, as I’ve already indicated, was whether, under the four- teenth amendment due process clause, recipients of government welfare assistance benefits are entitled to an evidentiary hearing prior to termination of benefits. The resolution of that issue turned on whether the recipient possessed a ‘property’ interest for procedural due process pur- poses. The government had argued that there was no right to receive welfare benefits, that such benefits were only a ‘privilege.’ It was this right/privilege distinction that the Court rejected. Citing Charles Reich, Justice Brennan wrote, ‘It may be realistic today to regard welfare entitlements as more like "property" than a "gratuity".’ But the determination that welfare recipients have a property interest was made only with respect to the question whether they have any procedural rights under the Constitution, not whether they have any sort of substantive right to receive those benefits. Thus, the case really does not provide clear evidence to support the contention that the Court was on the verge of recognizing something like a substantive constitutional right to mini- mum welfare. Perhaps in some future case the Court, had it not been reconstituted by Richard Nixon, might have headed in that direction, but that is sheer counterfactual speculation. It is important to be careful about distinguishing statutory social welfare rights and a con- stitutional welfare right. There is no doubt that during the late 1960s, there was a major expan- sion of statutory welfare rights. Prodded by the steam-rolling exhortations of President Lyndon Johnson, Congress enacted program after program in an overt effort to eradicate poverty by meeting the minimum economic needs of all Americans, but no political leader at the time urged translating such statutory rights into a substantive constitutional right. 19 See WE Forbath (note 10 above) at 598 fn 7and 612-613; WE Forbath ‘Lincoln, the Declaration, and the ‘Grisly, Undying Corpse of States’ Rights: History, Memory, and Imagination in the Constitution of a Southern Liberal’ (2004) 92 Georgetown LJ 709 at 709. 20 397 US at 264-265. 21 Ibid at 265. So, if Professor Sunstein’s Legal Realist theory does not provide a convincing explanation of why there are no constitutional socio-economic rights in the US, what is the reason? At least part of the explanation, I want to suggest, lies in American culture, but not the American excep- tionalist culture that Sunstein described. It lies, rather, in a tradition of anti-paternalist ideolo- gy that has strongly influenced American jurisprudence, both public and private, at least since the second half of the 19th century. The idea of enshrining social welfare rights in the Ur-text of the American polity, I suggest, is fundamentally incompatible with the American legal cul- ture of anti-paternalism. IV The Culture Of Anti-Paternalism In American Jurisprudence As a mode of legal thought and culture, anti-paternalism is closely related to two other cultur- al strands in American intellectual history. The first is Social Darwinism. In recent years there has been considerable discussion among American legal historians about the prevalence of Social Darwinist ideas in American legal thought since the second half of the nineteenth centu- ry. Revising the conventional account, which is usually attributed to the late Richard Hof- stadter,22 that depicts Social Darwinism as dominant since 1870, the consensus among American historians now is that the Social Darwinism did not dominate American legal thought during the late nineteenth century. But Social Darwinism, though closely related to anti-pater- nalism, is not identical with it. Anti-paternalism, or anti-protectionism as it might also be called, is captured by Albert Venn Dicey’s remark that ‘protection invariably involves disabili- ty.’23 It is primarily focused on the relationship between individuals and the state, viewing state measures to protect individuals from the hardships of life as inimical to the project of progres- sively developing a society of the fit. Social Darwinism, which reached its apogee in the United States during the Age of Enterprise, roughly from 1870 to 1900, tended to focus instead on the relationship between and the state and the market, as distinguished from society. Its thrust was certainly anti-protectionist, but its real attention was on the proper conditions of economic activity in a competitive market economy. To be sure, anti-paternalist rhetoric was often a sur- rogate for explicitly Social Darwinist rhetoric,24 but the forces opposing legal paternalism tend- ed to be more preoccupied with social progress rather than economic progress. If Social Darwinism has not dominated American legal culture since the late 1800s, anti-paternalism has. The key to understanding why socio-economic rights have never been recognized in American constitutional jurisprudence lies, I contend, in this feature of American legal tradition and culture. Assaults on legal paternalism have been a constant feature of American legal culture at least since the late 19th century. Today, anti-legal paternalism is often couched in the rhetoric of eco- nomics, but the American critique of legal paternalism is more than a matter of economic the- ory. It is based on a distinct social and, for many, moral vision, a vision that in some respects is an atavar of the 18th-century civic republican sociology of virtue, which taught that civic Socio-Economic Rights in American Perspective 13 22 See R Hofstadter Social Darwinism in American Thought (1955). 23 AV Dicey Lectures on Law and Public Opinion in England During the Nineteenth Century (1905) at 150 fn 1. 24 See A Soifer ‘The Paradox of Paternalism and Laissez-Faire Constitutionalism: United Supreme Court, 1888-1921’ (1987) 5 Law & History Review 252. 1 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E virtue was indispensable for a vigorous republic and that self-governance and economic inde- pendence were necessary conditions for civic virtue. In later incarnations, this vision empha- sized personal independence and self-reliance above all else. Unless your status placed you in one of the categories of persons deemed incapable of looking out for themselves – categories that in the 19th and early 20th centuries included racial groups such as Native Americans and African-Americans – you were held responsible for the material conditions of your own life. No one owed you a duty, legal or moral, to protect you against financial misfortune or to bail you out of economic distress. If people were to become legally entitled to protection against either their own ill-considered decisions or the vagaries of the market’s invisible hand, they would rap- idly lose the very personal qualities necessary for the civicly proper moral and political person- ality carefulness, determination, honesty, and above all, energy. The virtuous citizen was one who earned his wealth, paid his own way, satisfied all his debts, and responded to adversity with renewed vigor. He was, in short, the self-sufficient, productive person of integrity. The influence of this legal anti-paternalist thought on American constitutional jurisprudence during the period between 1870 and 1930 is well-known,25 for this was the heyday of what is commonly called laissez-faire constitutionalism. While the conventional view of judicial thought and practice during the era of laissez-faire constitutionalism has undergone a revision in recent years, with revisers softening the image of courts as intractably opposed to all and every form of interference with the workings of the market, there still remains little doubt that during this period courts tended to be hostile to legislation that they viewed as ‘class’ legisla- tion.26 This was especially true of legislation aimed at protecting discrete categories of workers from harsh working conditions and unfair terms of employment. That the culture of anti-pater- nalism was doing the real work behind the mask of freedom of contract is indicated by the fac- tual circumstances in which courts gave their constitutional approval to legislative regulations of the workplace. The best example is the famous 1908 case of Muller v Oregon,27 where the Supreme Court upheld a state statute limiting the number of hours women could work in laun- dries. The Court’s opinion rested squarely and explicitly on the factual assumption that women were naturally ‘at a disadvantage in the race for subsistence.’28 Women, along with children, Native Americans, and a few other social categories (such as ‘idiots’) were widely considered to be naturally in need of legal protection,29 so statutes of the sort involved in Muller did not run afoul of the consensus regarding anti-paternalism. During the Great Depression, which lasted from 1929 to 1941, attitudes about need, self- sufficiency, and legal protection changed profoundly in many respects. The Depression made it abundantly clear to most Americans that even the most virtuous and productive person could find herself in desperate circumstances for reasons completely beyond her control. As one legal historian has written, ‘The Great Depression sorely tested old assumptions . . . that economic well-being flowed from personal virtue, and that government had a limited role in promoting the collective social welfare.’30 Franklin Roosevelt’s election to the Presidency was due in no small measure to this sea change in the economic conditions of many hard-working ordinary 25 See ibid. 26 See ML Benedict ‘Laissez-Faire and Liberty: A Reevaluation of the Meaning and Origins of Laissez-Faire Constitutionalism’ (1985) 3 Law & History Review 293. 27 208 US 412 (1908). 28 Ibid at 421. 29 See eg JC Gray Restraints on the Alienation of Property (1895) at 170. 30 KL Hall The Magic Mirror (1989) at 267. Americans. His New Deal legislative programmes were directly aimed at providing govern- mental assistance to a wide array of Americans, including groups, such as White males, that in anti-paternalist ideology were considered lacking any excuse for legal protection. Yet even the Great Depression did not eradicate the culture of anti-paternalism. There was a change in attitude toward legal protectionism, to be sure, but that change had definite limits. While legal paternalism was accepted in the form of legislation, it was not accepted at a con- stitutional level. The New Deal introduced unprecedented legislation aimed at providing eco- nomic assistance to a broad cross-section of the American public, but at no point was there any serious discussion of a constitutional basis for governmental assistance to the poor, the sick, or the unemployed. Indeed, there was not even any proposal for a constitutional right to public assistance of any kind. Conspicuously, Franklin Roosevelt’s own Second Bill of Rights never included a proposal for constitutional action. The President anticipated that his proposals would be implemented solely through legislation. The same pattern existed during the next period of social-welfare activism, the era of the War on Poverty and the Great Society. Scholars have noted the ways in which the welfare-rights movement of the 1960s departed from prior social movements aimed at government assistance for the needy, notably by shifting from an emphasis on work to a focus on welfare.31 However, the two movements shared a common and exclusive method for implementing their vision of weaving socio-economic rights into the fabric of American law, and that exclusive method was legislation. As in the case of the New Deal, the welfare-rights activists of the 1960s, including Charles Reich, never proposed making social welfare a matter of constitutional right. There had been a shift away from the more robust version of anti-paternalist legal and political culture in the late 1960s, but that shift went only so far. The line between statutory and constitutional paternalism was not to be crossed. Why was that the case? Once the culture of anti-paternalism was relaxed, why didn’t it lead to constitutional action, either through constitutional amendment or through judicial interpre- tation? Here we have to turn our attention from culture to an institutional factor. That factor is the character of constitutional rights in the American legal system. Constitutional rights are different from their counterparts in many other countries. This is not the occasion for detailing all of these differences, but a few have to be noted to understand why the idea of statutory socio-economic rights has been accepted while a constitutional version of such rights has not. One difference has already been noted: in American jurisprudence legal rights, but especial- ly constitutional rights, are generally viewed as pragmatic tools rather than being purely expres- sive or aspirational.32 While statutory rights usually are viewed through the same pragmatic lens, there are instances in which statutes have been enacted despite substantial doubts about their judicial enforceability. In these instances lawmakers view the harm likely to result from the fact that a statute’s failure to deliver its practical promise as outweighed by the benefit gained by the statute’s expressive effect. This is not the case with respect to constitutional norms, however. The idea of a constitutional provision that lacks judicial enforceability is anathema to the American legal system. Legal unenforceability, real or projected, has both pre- vented adoption of constitutional amendments (as in the case of the Equal Rights Amendment) and prompted repeal of amendments already enacted (as in the case of the Eighteenth Socio-Economic Rights in American Perspective 15 31 Forbath (note 10 above) at 604. 32 For a discussion of the expression vs pragmatic character of American constitutional rights, see Sunstein (note 1 above) at 140-145 Amendment, which prohibited the manufacture, sale, and transport of intoxicating liquor). A statute that doesn’t do something is tolerable; a comparable constitutional right is not. A related institutional factor is the importance in the American constitutional scheme of maintaining the realm of ordinary, ie majoritarian politics. A right that is strictly statutory does not remove the subject matter of the right from the realm of majoritarian politics. The matter is always on the political table, subject to legislative control and change through the processes of ordinary politics. Elevating a right to constitutional level, however, poses the counter-majori- tarian difficulty. The right becomes a ‘Super Right,’ removed from the realm of ordinary poli- tics and majoritarian control. In a country in which ‘democracy’ means majoritarian control, the decision to make an individual right a constitutional right is taken with great caution. Better to err on the side of leaving the matter subject to legislative control, the thought is. So, the default mode regarding constitutional revision of any sort is inaction. This general hesitation regarding recognition of new constitutional rights, combined with the residual force of the culture of anti-paternalism, in my judgment, explains the absence of con- stitutional socio-economic rights better than Professor Sunstein’s theory. Even in the absence of a change of membership of the Supreme Court in 1970, I think it highly unlikely that a sub- stantive social welfare right would have been added to the constitutional roster. 1 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E The ‘Politics of Need Interpretation’* and the Adjudication of Socio-Economic Rights Claims in South Africa** D A N I E B R A N D Senior lecturer, Department of Public Law, University of Pretoria I Introduction Against the backdrop of a transformative constitution, writes Karl Klare, an important question to ask of the work product of judges is the extent to which it either erodes or reinforces discur- sive politics, opens up or limits space for political contestation, ‘deepen[s] democratic culture’ or ignores it.1 Judgments and interpretations that reinforce participatory politics advance the Constitution’s transformative ethos, those that do the opposite, unconscious of their political role, frustrate it.2 Klare himself proposes one way in which judges can through their work deep- en democratic culture. By being candid about the political nature of their work, by laying bare the extra-legal political concerns that influence their interpretations and decisions, they can ren- der themselves accountable and so create space for political critique of their work product.3 But we know, as does Klare, that important as such candour might be, the difficulty facing judges in this respect is more complex than this, that the tension between rights and democracy is more intractable.4 The law, including adjudication, works in a variety of ways to destruct the socie- tal structures necessary for politics, to close down space for political contestation. To work in a * Nancy Fraser ‘Talking about Needs: Interpretive Contests as Political Conflicts in Welfare-State Societies’ (1989) 99 Ethics 291 at 292. ** My thanks to Beth Goldblatt, Sandra Liebenberg, André van der Walt, Johan van der Walt and Stuart Wilson for their comments when I presented earlier versions of this paper at the July 2004 South African Journal of Human Rights Conference in Johannesburg and the July 2004 Stellenbosch Institute for Ad- vanced Studies seminar on theories of socio-economic rights in Stellenbosch, and to Karin van Marle and Stu Woolman for reading and commenting on various drafts. Mistakes are my own. 1 K Klare ‘Legal Culture and Transformative Constitutionalism’ (1998) 14 SAJHR 146 at 164-165 and 171. As the word and terms ‘politics’ or ‘political contestation’ and ‘democracy’ will often appear in this paper, I would do well at this stage already to say what I mean with them. I refer to politics in what Nancy Fraser ‘Talking About Needs: Interpretive Contests as Political Conflicts in Welfare-State Societies’ (1989) 99 Ethics 291 at 297 has described as a discursive sense – in this sense, ‘something is “political” if it is con- tested across a range of different discursive arenas and among a range of different publics’. Politics in this sense is contrasted with politics in the institutional sense (‘a matter is deemed political if it is handled direct- ly in the institutions of the official governmental system, including parliaments, administrative apparatuses, and the like’) and politics in the official sense (‘what is “political” … contrasts with what is handled in insti- tutions like the “family” or the “economy”, which are defined as outside the official-political system’). 2 Ibid 165. 3 Ibid 164-165. 4 Ibid 171-172. 1 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E transformative way, judges have to be aware of and attempt to take account of all of them. In this paper, I focus on one way in which courts can close down space for politics that judges should be aware of: courts can erode participatory politics by invoking and therefore reinforcing in their judgments and interpretations certain rhetorical strategies that are used by participants in the political discourse around poverty and need in our new welfare state to depoliticise the terms of that debate. I analyse a number of the socio-economic rights cases that the Constitutional Court and Supreme Court of Appeal have decided to date – Soobramoney,5 Grootboom,6 Treatment Action Campaign,7 Khosa,8 Port Elizabeth Municipality9 and Modderklip10 – and track the use by courts of this depoliticizing rhetoric. At the same time I identify from the cases countervailing trends that suggest ways in which courts can subvert or avoid this particular depoliticising effect of their work. II Drawing the Limits of the Political Poverty and basic need – those social problems of hunger, homelessness and inadequate access to health care, social assistance and education that give rise to socio-economic rights litigation – are questions of major political concern. These issues occupy a significant part of the discourse in our formal political institutions. In the competitive environment of parliamentary politics, different understandings of, for example, the causes of HIV/Aids, of who bears responsibility for providing treatment for people living with HIV/Aids and of how best to treat them are centrally important subjects of political contestation and forms of political currency. These issues are also central to informal participatory forms of politics. An issue like inadequate access to basic services such as water and electricity gives rise to popular demonstrations and constitutes the raison d’être of informal social movements who engage in direct political action; uncertainty about the nature and extent and the causes of homelessness sustains polit- ical debates in the print and visual media; and questions about whether or not South Africa should extend its social assistance system occupy the discursive politics of social activists and academics. In sum, in South Africa ‘talk about people’s needs is an important species of political discourse’, ‘has been institutionalised as a major vocabulary of politic[s]’ and is ‘an idiom in which political conflict is played out and through which inequalities are symbolically elaborated and challenged’.11 At the same time there is in the different political discourses about these questions a perva- sive tendency toward their depoliticisation – that is, a tendency to talk about them in such a way that they are bracketed as non-political, not subject to or not capable of being subjected to political contestation. When Government publicly warns that further extension of the social assistance system would lead to the inculcation in poor people of a ‘culture of dependency’,12 the implication is that poor people somehow are themselves to blame for their predicament, that they are poor because they are lazy or lack entrepreneurial vigour. The political causes of their poverty are hidden, papered over. When ordinary people lament the enormity of poverty 5 Soobramoney v Minister of Health, KwaZulu-Natal 1998 (1) SA 765 (CC) (Soobramoney). 6 Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC) (Grootboom). 7 Minister of Health v Treatment Action Campaign 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC) (Treatment Action Campaign). 8 Khosa v Minister of Social Development 2004 (6) SA 505 (CC) (Khosa). 9 Port Elizabeth Municipality v Various Occupiers 2004 (12) BCLR 1268 (CC) (PE Municipality). 10 Modderfontein Squatters v Modderklip Boerdery (Pty) Ltd 2004 (6) SA 40 (SCA) (Modderklip). 11 Fraser (note 1 above) at 291. 12 See the remarks of government spokesperson Joel Netshitenze, in response to the proposal by the Taylor Commission of Inquiry into a Comprehensive System of Social Security for South Africa for a universal basic income grant, saying that it would amount to a ‘handout’ and would encourage a culture of entitle- ment. Netshitenze further indicated that the cabinet prefers a public works programme, because it believes in South Africa, pointing to the inexorable impact of a globalised economy, or an inadequate natural resource base as its cause, something similar happens. Poverty is attributed to forces over which we have no control, with which political engagement is impossible or futile.13 Against this background, Nancy Fraser describes what she calls the process of ‘need inter- pretation’ – of giving meaning to the concepts basic need and poverty, determining their caus- es, deciding which needs and which kinds or degrees of poverty merit state intervention and deciding what the best ways are to address instances of deprivation – as follows: [N]eeds talk appears as a site of struggle where groups with unequal discursive (and non-discursive) resources compete to establish as hegemonic their respective interpre- tations of legitimate social needs. Dominant groups articulate need interpretations intended to exclude, defuse and/or co-opt counterinterpretations. Subordinate or oppo- sitional groups, on the other hand, articulate need interpretations intended to chal- lenge, displace, and/or modify dominant ones. 14 In short, the political discourse around issues of poverty and basic need is a process of politici- sation, depoliticisation and repoliticisation of the issues at stake. Particular questions of depri- vation – say inadequate access to anti-retroviral treatment for people living with HIV/AIDS, or insecurity of tenure for the propertyless – are inserted into political discourse, claimed as legiti- mate political concerns through the oppositional social action of social pressure groups or polit- ical movements. Dominant societal groups, intent on immunizing their privileged position as property owners or hiding their complicity in the suffering of people living with HIV/AIDS or justifying to themselves their position of relative privilege, attempt to remove these issues from the search light of robust political contestation, to depoliticise them. Subordinate groups – the people living with HIV/AIDS or the propertyless – in turn, intent on challenging their positions of relative deprivation and on claiming from society the assistance to which they feel entitled, work to retain these questions as issues of political concern, to politicise or repoliticise them. In this political to-and-fro, this process of depoliticisation and repoliticisation, a set of stock de- politicizing rhetorical strategies are usually employed. The first of these strategies is to ‘domesticate’ issues of poverty and need – to describe them as issues that fall within the domestic rather than the political sphere. As such, these issues can be cast as private or familial issues rather than public or political.15 Martha Fineman describes the nature and effect of this domestication strategy as follows: The private family is the social institution that is relied upon to raise children and care for the ill, the needy and the dependent. Ideally it performs these tasks as a self- contained and self-sufficient unit without demanding public resources to do so. In the societal division of labor among institutions, the private family bears the burden of dependency, not the public state. Resort to the state is considered a failure. By according to the private family responsibility for inevitable dependency, society directs dependency away from the state and privatizes it. 16 Politics of Need Interpretation 19 ‘able-bodied’ South Africans should enjoy ‘the opportunity, the dignity and rewards of work’ (quoted in A Habib & C Skinner ‘The Poor Must Fend for Themselves’ (04-08-2002) Sunday Times 14). 13 LA Williams ‘Welfare and Legal Entitlements: The Social Roots of Poverty’ in D Kairys (ed) The Politics of Law. A Progressive Critique (1998, 3d edition) 569 at 569. 14 Fraser (note 1 above) at 296. 15 Fraser (note 1 above) at 299. 16 MLA Fineman ‘Masking Dependency: The Political Role of Family Rhetoric’ (1995) 81 Virginia LR 2181 at 2205. 2 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E In a patriarchal, capitalist society such as ours, the depoliticizing effect of the domestication of an issue is profound. One needs think only of how recently still forced sex within a marriage was in South Africa not regarded as rape but as a ‘private matter’ between husband and wife, to be reminded of how startlingly strong the perceived normative split between the public (political) and the private (personal) still is, or until recently was, in this respect. The second common depoliticisation strategy employed by dominant groups is the personal- isation of need and dependence – the status of poverty, of being dependent is attributed to the personal character traits, the failure, the abnormality of poor people themselves, rather than to the social, political and economic forces that actually shape it. Thomas Ross writes that this rhetorical process of personalisation of poverty takes place in two stages. The first rhetorical step is the creation of the ‘abstraction the “poor”’ as a distinct class of people ‘who are them, not us’.17 This makes possible the second rhetorical move – the attribution to the poor of moral weakness. To describe the poor as morally weak, they first have to exist as a separate group. This creation of otherness has a further result: it makes it possible for the middle class and the affluent to proclaim not only the moral weakness of the poor, but also their deviance, their abnormality.18 In similar vein, Lucy Williams relates how popular understandings of poverty and dependence in the US distinguish between the ‘deserving’ and the ‘undeserving’ poor. Poverty or dependence that cannot be explained as the result of ‘natural’ factors such as natu- ral disaster, physical or mental disability or age is undeserving of social assistance. Such ‘unde- serving’ poverty, in the absence of a ‘natural’ cause, so the assumptions go, can only be ex- plained by the personal degeneracy and deviance of the poor person, who is to blame for her own position and consequently doesn’t deserve assistance.19 Perceptions or assumptions about the moral degeneracy of the poor and their consequent blameworthiness for their predicament are prevalent in South Africa. South Africa’s social assistance system is built on a distinction between deserving and undeserving poor. It is almost wholly special needs based – regular grants are paid only to groups such as children, older people and the disabled, who cannot be blamed for the condition of poverty, while no provision is made for social assistance to people who are poor, but ‘able bodied’. Government’s reaction to the proposal made in 2002 by the Taylor Commission of Inquiry into a Comprehensive Social Security system for South Africa that a universal basic income grant should be introduced is illuminating in this respect. Govern- ment rejected the proposal and introduced instead an extended Public Works Programme. At the time, a government spokesperson explained this move as motivated by the fear that a basic income grant would breed in poor people a ‘culture of entitlement’ or dependency, and went on to say that a public works programme is apposite, as ‘able-bodied’ South Africans should enjoy ‘the opportunity, the dignity and rewards of work’.20 A third rhetorical strategy employed by dominant groups within the political discourse about need and poverty to depoliticise the debate is the naturalisation of poverty. Poverty and depri- vation is depoliticised by it being attributed to ‘natural’ causes, wholly outside of the control of society. This process of naturalisation can occur in two ways. The first is through the act of 17 Thomas Ross ‘The Rhetoric of Poverty: Their Immorality, Our Helplessness’ (1991) 79 Georgetown LJ 1499 at 1499-1500. 18 Ibid 1500-1501. 19 Williams (note 13 above) at 569. See also Ross (note 17 above) at 1501-1502; and N Fraser & L Gordon ‘A Genealogy of Dependency: Tracing a Keyword of the US Welfare State’ (1994) 19 Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society 309 (reproduced in LA Williams Welfare Law (2001) 47) at 323-324. 20 Joel Netshitenze, quoted by Habib & Skinner (note 12 above). throwing one’s hands in the air and succumbing to the enormity of the problem of poverty – simply saying that there is so much of it that it will always be with us. The second is through the act of according causes to poverty, but then inexorable causes over which society has no control, for example the uncompromising, impersonal forces of the global market. Common to both these assertions is the idea that poverty is somehow ‘naturally’ part of the structure of our society, and will consequently always be there, whatever we do: ‘The causes of poverty, we assume, are a product of a complex set of factors tied to politics, culture, history, psychology and philosophy. Thus, only in a radically different world might poverty cease to exist. And, whatever the extent of [our] … powers … , radically remaking the world is not one of them.’21 The fourth and final depoliticizing rhetorical strategy employed in the political discourse about poverty is the process of instrumentalisation of needs-talk.22 The political discourse about poverty and need occurs in different discursive arenas – within informal social move- ments and pressure groups, more formal organs of civil society such as NGO’s and academia and, finally, within official discursive arenas such as Parliament or specialist administrative agencies.23 These different discursive arenas occupy positions of relative power in the struggle to determine and fix meaning in the interpretation of questions of poverty and need. The descriptions given to poverty and need in the official discursive arenas such as Parliament and specialist administrative agencies are officially sanctioned. As such they exert an authoritative influence on the political discourse around poverty and need. At the same time the interpreta- tion of poverty, need and deprivation that takes place in these official discursive arenas is explic- itly depoliticizing. When Parliament, or a department of state speak about a particular need and engage in the interpretation of that need, they do so with a specific purpose. The need in ques- tion has been legitimized as deserving of state intervention and their purpose is to find the best way to satisfy it – they are in the process of ‘translating politicized needs into administerable needs.’24 As such, the previously politicized issues with which they are confronted become ‘technical problems for managers and planners … in contradistinction to political matters.’25 This process of translation depoliticises in two ways. First, it brackets the issues in question as technically complex issues with which ordinary, non-expert participants in the discourse on poverty cannot usefully engage. Second, the subordinate participants in the discourse are repo- sitioned – whereas before they where active participants in the process of interpretation of their needs, engaged in political action, they now become the passive recipients of services – their pre- defined needs are administered to them through a process of therapeutic assistance.26 As a result, their political engagement is negated. The different strategies of depoliticisation described above are politically motivated – they are used to further particular political agendas and are as such in themselves acutely political.27 Dependence and deprivation is attributed to the personality traits of poor people so that the complicity of the legal and political system in creating their predicament can be obscured and challenge to these systems can be avoided and so that positions of relative affluence can be jus- Politics of Need Interpretation 21 21 Ross (note 17 above) at 1501. 22 Fraser (note 1 above) at 299. 23 Ibid 295. 24 Ibid 306. 25 Ibid 299. See also J Habermas ‘Law as Medium and Law as Institution’ in G Teubner (ed) Dilemmas of Law in the Welfare State (1986) 204 at 210. 26 Habermas (note 25 above) at 210; see also Fraser (note 1 above) at 307. 27 Fraser (note 1 above) at 298: ‘[O]ne of the primary stakes of social conflict in late-capitalist societies is pre- cisely where the limits of the political will be drawn.’ 2 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E tified – it is the fault of poor people themselves that they are poor and of no one else. Poverty is described as inevitable, as a constant presence in society so that personal and collective inac- tion with respect to it can be justified – society can assert its helplessness in the face of ‘natu- ral’ deprivation and so avoid having to do anything about it. In broad terms all these strategies of depoliticisation are aimed to preserve the status quo, both by immunizing it from attack by hiding its complicity in creating and maintaining poverty and by justifying inaction in the face of poverty and hardship. As such these acts of depoliticisation are cause for concern: they con- stitute attempts by society to assert its helplessness in the face of poverty, to get away with doing nothing about something that indeed is, at least to some extent, within its control.28 That the law is determinatively involved in the discourse about the political stakes of pover- ty and need is a point that hardly requires making. Precisely the social provisioning activities of the welfare state – state provision of housing, of health care services, of education and of other social services – are regulated by vast, complicated and ever-expanding networks of law, in the widest possible sense of that word: Formal legislation, administrative rules and decisions and, more recently, constitutional or statutory welfare rights elaborated in judgements by courts. The law in question is of a particular kind – its is ‘regulatory’, ‘instrumentalised’ law, aimed not, as law traditionally was, at resolving particular and discrete disputes, but at regulating, guiding, constituting and giving effect to the social provisioning programmes and goals of the state. As such it is part of and in certain respects constitutive of the political discourse around poverty and need. South Africa certainly also stands under the mark of this kind of, what has come to be called ‘juridification’.29 Although the Apartheid-state already operated according to its fair share of regulatory law, South Africa has, post liberation, seen an explosion of law intended to control, guide and give effect to the ‘societal guidance intentions’30 of the new State. Courts’ socio-economic rights judgements, and the doctrine established and elaborated in those judgements, form a significant part of our process of juridification. The effects of juridification – the role of law in the welfare state, its impact and the conse- quences of its operation there – have for long attracted scholarly attention. Scholars have first analysed and questioned the effect of legal expansion on the law itself, arguing for instance that, because law is bound to fail in its social engineering role, juridification causes a crisis of credi- bility for law,31 and that the instrumentalisation of law for social purposes threatens its con- ceptual structures,32 rendering it internally incoherent and ‘disintegrat[ing] basic legal values and the unity of the legal system.’33 More pertinently, juridification scholars have also devoted considerable attention to the effect of juridification on the areas of life and society into which law newly expands or in which 28 Ross (note 17 above) at 1509-1513. 29 ‘Juridification’ is the term used to describe the phenomenon of growth of regulation or growth of law in the welfare state. See, for a good synopsis of both the phenomenon of juridification itself and the body of schol- arship that has developed from the study of its nature, causes and effects, JWG van der Walt The Twilight of Legal Subjectivity: Towards a Deconstructive Republican Theory of Law (1995) unpublished LLD dis- sertation, Rand Afrikaans University at 319-326; see also the various contributions in G Teubner (ed) Dilemmas of Law in the Welfare State (1986) and Juridification of Social Spheres (1987). 30 G Teubner ‘The Transformation of Law in the Welfare State’ in G Teubner (ed) Dilemmas of Law in the Welfare State (1986) 3 (Teubner ‘Transformation’) at 3. 31 G Teubner ‘Juridification Concepts, Aspects, Limits, Solutions’ in G Teubner (ed) Juridification of Social Spheres (1987) (Teubner ‘Concepts’) at 6. 32 N Luhman ‘The Self-Reproduction of Law and its Limits’ in G Teubner (ed) Dilemmas of Law in the Welfare State (1986) 111, in general. 33 Teubner ‘Transformation’ (note 30 above) at 4. See also Van der Walt (note 29 above) at 324. existing regulation densifies. In this respect juridification commentators have explored and analysed a familiar tension: The tension between rights and democracy34 or the ‘ambivalence of guarantees of and denials of freedom’35 that is occasioned by the process of juridification – the problem that, whilst juridification patently has an emancipatory intent (guaranteeing, for instance, access to basic social benefits to protect against the depredations of the market), it operates simultaneously in a repressive fashion in that it limits the potential for radical and crit- ical political action.36 Juridification – including the work of courts in the process of interpreting and applying socio-economic rights – can exercise this stilling effect on radical and critical political action first by destructing or subverting the various forms of social organisation upon which such action depends.37 Johan van der Walt, for example, refers to the ‘individualizing tendency’ of juridification – rights and the individual entitlements emanating from them that are inserted into the social sphere through juridification ‘take[ ] the place of spontaneous communal sup- port in family as well as in local community life’, so that collective organisation and collective political action is impaired, replaced by self-interest seeking action.38 This kind of ‘privatisa- tion of right’ has been well documented in historical accounts of labour movements in Europe, where the creeping legalism of juridification has contributed to the transformation of these movements from collective bodies advocating the emancipation of workers as a class, to ‘encor- porated organisations’ representing the individual consumer interests of their members. Membership of the group loses its political dimension, becoming instead an instrument for the furtherance of individual interests.39 Juridification further works to ‘gloss over’ and ‘pacify’ political conflict and contestation.40 The intrusion of rights and the language of rights in the social sphere runs the risk of promot- ing ‘a false expectation in disadvantaged individuals and groups that the pursuit of legal rights through the courts can effect lasting social change’ whereas ‘rights…operate instead to…chan- nel potentially radical demands for change into legal claims which, by definition, will not be disruptive of the social and economic status quo.’41 But juridification can also diminish the potential for critical political action in another way. The law can, through the language it uses, through the interpretations of need and poverty that it authorizes, confirm and legitimate the depoliticizing strategies that participants in the politi- cal debate around need employ. Courts can play a particularly significant role in this respect. Politics of Need Interpretation 23 34 See also in this respect the various contributions in H Botha, AJ van der Walt & JWG van der Walt Rights and Democracy in a Transformative Constitution (2004). 35 Habermas (note 25 above) at 209. 36 Van der Walt (note 29 above) at 323 (juridification is aimed at ‘serving the goal of social integration, yet … merely contribute[s] to the process of social disintegration’). 37 J Habermas (note 25 above) at 211: ‘ … [W]hile the welfare state guarantees are intended to serve the goal of social integration, they nevertheless promote the disintegration of life relations.’ 38 Van der Walt (note 29 above) at 324. See also AAG Peters ‘Law as Critical Discussion’ in G Teubner (ed) Dilemmas of Law in the Welfare State (1986) 250 at 276-277. 39 Peters (note 38 above) at 276. See also S Simitis ‘Juridification of Labor Relations’ in G Teubner (ed) Juridification of Social Spheres (1987) 113 at 132-134. 40 Van der Walt (note 29 above) at 324. 41 M Jackman ‘Constitutional Rhetoric and Social Justice: Reflections on the Justiciability Debate’ in J Bakan & D Schneiderman (eds) Social Justice and the Constitution: Perspectives on a Social Union for Canada (1992) 17 at 22. See in this respect S Wilson ‘Taming the Constitution: Rights and Reform in the South African Education System’ (2004) 20 SAJHR 418 at 423-424, who points out how the Department of Education has effectively co-opted rights talk to ‘provide ideological window-dressing for policies and prac- tices, which actually countenance significant limits on the very rights they are supposed to advance’ (at 424). 2 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E The particular rhetorical power that their processes and their work-product enjoy in our democracy has been noted before – in Karl Klare’s words, we may ‘legitimately expect’ adjudi- cation ‘to innovate and model intellectual and institutional practices’ in our democracy.42 To some extent at least, and it might be to only a very small extent,43 but nevertheless, when courts speak, people listen and sometimes copy. When courts engage with issues of poverty and need in socio-economic rights cases they also engage with and participate in the political discourse around poverty and need referred to above. This happens in different ways. First, courts’ adju- dication of socio-economic rights claims becomes part of the political discourse, even a medi- um through which this discourse partly plays out. Civil society organisations and social move- ments regard and use socio-economic rights litigation as tools of political struggle not separate from, but as part of that struggle.44 Court judgments in these kinds of cases once handed down become rallying points, political currency in their struggles. Second, courts also occupy a sym- bolic, or perhaps more accurately, an exemplary role with respect to poverty and need dis- courses – their vocabulary, the conceptual structures they rely on, the rhetorical strategies they employ infiltrate and so influence and shape the political discourses around poverty and need. This is, despite its protestations to the contrary,45 particularly true of the Constitutional Court, because of its prominence and its symbolic significance – one can but think of the extent to which the ‘reasonableness’ test that the Court developed in Grootboom and Treatment Action Campaign with which to evaluate the state’s social provisioning activities has shaped civil soci- ety monitoring of planning and delivery with respect to social services and the political advo- cacy informed by that monitoring.46 Now, as I pointed out at the start of this section, the political discourse about poverty and need in the welfare state in which law is a participant consists not only in a political process of the interpretation of need, but also in a political process of drawing the limits of the political, of determining which issues related to poverty and need are legitimately subject to political con- testation. In the political struggle around issues of poverty and deprivation rhetorical strategies of domestication, personalisation, naturalisation and instrumentalisation are employed by usu- ally the socially dominant participants to depoliticise issues in need-interpretation, to cast them as non-political, as falling outside the scope of legitimate political contestation. Were courts to invoke these rhetorical strategies in their interpretation and judgement when deciding socio- economic rights cases, they could potentially exert a profound depoliticising influence on the 42 Klare (note 1 above) at 147. 43 Wilson (note 41 above) at 420-421. 44 See ibid 436-442 for an account of use of the right to education in this ‘instrumental’ sense by social move- ments and NGO’s in struggles pertaining to basic education. With respect to the use of litigation in this sense, see M Heywood ‘Preventing Mother-to-Child HIV Transmission in South Africa: Background, Strategies and Outcomes of the Treatment Action Campaign Case Against the Minister of Health’ (2003) 19 SAJHR 278 at 314-315; and S Liebenberg ‘South Africa’s Evolving Jurisprudence on Socio-Economic Rights: An Effective Tool in Challenging Poverty?’ (2002) 6 Law, Democracy and Development 159 at 159. 45 See eg Treatment Action Campaign (note 7 above) paras 20-21: ‘[T]he issue of HIV/AIDS has for some time been fraught with an unusual degree of political, ideological and emotional contention … [S]ome of this contention and emotion has spilt over into this case … Ultimately, however, we have found it possible to cut through the overlay of contention and arrive at a straightforward and unanimous conclusion.’ For a dis- cussions see H Botha ‘Freedom and Constraint in Constitutional Adjudication’ (2004) 20 SAJHR 249 at 249-250 and K Van Marle ‘Revisiting the Politics of Post-Apartheid Constitutional Interpretation’ (2003) TSAR 549 at 552-553. 46 See eg J Streak & J Wehner ‘Children’s Socio-economic Rights in the South African Constitution: Towards a Framework for Monitoring Implementation’ in E Coetzee & J Streak (eds) Monitoring Child Socio- Economic Rights in South Africa: Achievements and Challenges (2004) 50 at 79. political discourse around poverty and need. Invoking such depoliticizing rhetorical strategies will in the first place significantly determine the outcomes of their decisions – courts, as do those in the political discourse, usually invoke such strategies so as to justify their avoidance of particular issues, to assert, as Thomas Ross has described it, their helplessness with respect to a particular aspect of poverty or deprivation.47 Not only does that mean that the court does not decide the issue in question. It also means that substantive political discussion of it in court is precluded.48 In the second place, invocation of these rhetorical strategies could also, because of the rhetorical power that the language of courts enjoy in our political discourse around poverty and need, influence and shape that discourse, contribute to drawing the limits of the political there. To recapitulate: In this section I described ways in which courts can work to erode and limit political contestation. I focused on one particular such way: The invocation of courts in their interpretation and judgement in socio-economic rights cases of depoliticising rhetorical strate- gies of domestication, personalisation, naturalisation and instrumentalisation of issues of poverty and basic need. I pointed out that courts’ reliance on these strategies could limit the transformative impact of their decisions and could work to depoliticize the political discourse around issues of poverty and basic need. In the following section, I proceed to analyse a num- ber of judgements with a view to identifying courts’ invocation of the depoliticising rhetorical strategies discussed above. In addition, I point to various countervailing strategies operating in these judgements that might aid courts in managing their impact on the space for political con- testation. III Depoliticisation and Repoliticisation in the Courts (A) INTRODUCTION In my review of the case law to follow, I focus on a particular kind of socio-economic rights case: cases in which the enforcement of an affirmative constitutional duty – that is, a duty to do something rather than a negative duty to refrain from doing something49 – was at issue. The Constitutional Court has to date decided four cases that were explicitly formulated as such. In Soobramoney v Minister of Health, KwaZulu-Natal,50 it denied an application for an order that a state hospital provide dialysis treatment to the applicant, finding that the guidelines according to which the hospital decided whether to provide the treatment were not unreason- able51 and were applied rationally and in good faith to the applicant.52 As such, the Court held Politics of Need Interpretation 25 47 Ross (note 17 above) at 1511. 48 Ibid. 49 The distinction between affirmative and negative duties is of course empty - it is often impossible to dis- tinguish between positive and negative constitutional duties and the strategic conclusions that are drawn on the basis of the distinction are false; see D Brand ‘Introduction to Socio-Economic Rights in the South African Constitution’ in D Brand & CH Heyns (eds) Socio-economic Rights in South Africa (2005) 1 at 10- 12. Nevertheless, the Constitutional Court has adopted this distinction and has developed its doctrine with respect to the enforcement of socio-economic rights with it in mind. 50 Soobramoney (note 5 above). 51 Ibid paras 24-28. 52 Ibid para 29. 2 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E that the denial of treatment did not breach the section 27(1) right of everyone to have access to health care services.53 In Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom,54 the Court heard a claim that the state was obliged to provide homeless people with shelter. It declared the state’s housing programme inconsistent with section 26(1) of the Constitution.55 In Minister of Health v Treatment Action Campaign,56 the Court held that the state’s policy not to provide Nevirapine at all public health facilities to prevent the mother-to-child transmission (MTCT) of HIV at birth, as well as the general failure by the state to adopt an adequate plan to combat MTCT of HIV, breached section 27(1) of the Constitution. The Court held that the state’s measures to prevent MTCT of HIV breached its duties in terms of section 27(1) of the Constitution,57 declared as much and directed the state to remedy its programme.58 In Khosa v Minister of Social Development,59 the Court held sections of the Social Assistance Act60 excluding permanent residents from access to social assistance grants inconsistent with section 9(3) (the prohibition on unfair discrimination)61 and section 27(1)(c) (the right to have access to social assistance)62 of the Constitution. The Court read words into the Act to remedy the constitutional defect.63 In addition to these four, I also consider two further cases, in which affirmative duties came into play indirectly. In Modderfontein Squatters v Modderklip Boerdery (Pty) Ltd,64 the Supreme Court of Appeal was confronted with a claim brought by a private landowner that the state was constitutionally obliged to enforce and carry out an eviction order that he had obtained in terms of section 4 of the Prevention of Illegal Eviction from and Unlawful Occupation of Land Act (PIE)65 against squatters illegally occupying his land. The Court held that the state was indeed obliged to protect the claimant’s right to property against invasion by unlawful occupiers.66 However, at the same time, the state was obliged to protect the right of the squatters to have access to adequate housing.67 The Court consequently ordered the state to pay damages to Modderklip to make good the breach of its right to property and the State’s failure to protect against that breach,68 and to allow the squatters to remain on Modderklip’s land until alternative land is made available to them by the state.69 In effect, the 53 Ibid para 36. The application was argued around the sec 27(3) right not to be refused emergency medical treatment and on the right to life. The Court denied the application in these respects, holding that, because health care rights were explicitly protected in the Constitution, it was unnecessary to rely on the right to life (para 19) and that sec 27(3) did not apply to the applicant’s case, because his was not an emergency situa- tion (para 21) and sec 27(3) was a right not arbitrarily to be refused emergency medical treatment where it was available, instead of a positive right to make available emergency medical treatment where it was not (para 20). The Court on its own initiative proceeded to consider the claim on the basis of sec 27(1) (para 22). 54 Grootboom (note 6 above). 55 Ibid para 95. 56 Treatment Action Campaign (note 7 above). 57 Ibid para 95. 58 Ibid para 135. 59 Khosa (note 8 above). 60 Social Assistance Act 59 of 1992. 61 Khosa (note 8 above) para 77. 62 Ibid para 85. 63 Ibid paras 89 & 98. 64 Modderklip (note 10 above). 65 Prevention of Illegal Eviction from and Unlawful Occupation of Land Act 19 of 1998 (PIE). 66 Modderklip (note 10 above) para 21. 67 Ibid para 22. 68 Ibid paras 43 & 52. 69 Ibid paras 43 & 52. order required the state to buy the land so that the squatters could remain there, without con- tinuing to infringe Modderklip Boerdery’s property rights.70 In Port Elizabeth Municipality v Various Occupiers,71 the state had applied for an order to evict illegal occupants from private- ly owned land in terms of section 6 of PIE.72 The Constitutional Court confirmed the Supreme Court of Appeal’s decision denying the eviction order, in part because suitable alternative land was not available to the evictees.73 (B) SOOBRAMONEY, GROOTBOOM AND TREATMENT ACTION CAMPAIGN: AN INSTITUTIONAL UNDERSTANDING OF DEMOCRACY Soobramoney, Grootboom and Treatment Action Campaign, although they exhibit instances of the Court resisting the depoliticizing strategies described above (the court resists the person- alisation of poverty by emphasising the economic, political and social causes of poverty)74 most prominently show pervasive strategies of depoliticization. The Court engages in both the domestication and the instrumentalisation of the issues before it. The most striking example of domestication employed as a depoliticising rhetorical strategy comes from Sachs J’s concurring opinion in Soobramoney. An inordinate portion of this opin- ion75 is devoted to an explanation why the Court was unable to intervene on behalf of Mr Soobramoney – not why in a substantive sense his claim must fail,76 but why the Court could not engage with the issues raised by his claim. Indeed the opinion can perhaps best be described as a decision not to decide – a rather extreme example of what Robert Cover has called ‘the judi- cial can’t’.77 Sachs J invokes the usual arguments of institutional incapacity and limited resources to justify his ‘can’t’. He argues, persuasively, that the issues with respect to Mr Soobramoney’s medical treatment were technical medical questions that the court is not equipped to decide78 and ‘toll[s] the bell of lack of resources’,79 pointing out that ‘if governments were unable to con- fer any benefit on any person unless it conferred an identical benefit on all, the only viable option would be to confer no benefit on anybody.’80 But then he goes further still. Referring to US case Politics of Need Interpretation 27 70 Although explicitly indicating that it would not be proper for it to order the state to expropriate the land in question (ibid para 41), the Court does point out that, in light of its order, it would be the sensible thing for the state to do, to expropriate the land (para 43). The state took Modderklip on appeal to the Constitutional Court. The Constitutional Court decision was reported on 16 May 2005; confirming the SCA decision in its effect, albeit for other reasons based on secs 1, 34 rather than 25, 26 of the Constitution. 71 PE Municipality (note 9 above). 72 PIE (note 64 above) sec 6(3)(c). 73 The Supreme Court of Appeal decision is reported as Baartman v Port Elizabeth Municipality 2004 (1) SA 560 (SCA). 74 See eg Grootboom (note 6 above) para 3 (‘The … people with whom we are concerned in these proceed- ings lived in appalling conditions, decided to move out and illegally occupied someone else’s land. They were evicted and left homeless. The root cause of their problems is the intolerable conditions under which they were living while waiting in the queue for their turn to be allocated low-cost housing.’). 75 8 of the 11 paragraphs; Soobramoney (note 5 above) paras 52-59. 76 Substantive engagement with the claim is limited to a single paragraph, in which Sachs J expressed his agree- ment with Chaskalson P’s finding for the Court that Mr Soobramoney’s condition was not an emergency medical condition and did not qualify him for the protection of section 27(3); ibid para 51. 77 R Cover Justice Accused: Anti-Slavery and the Judiciary Process (1975) at 119-120. 78 Soobramoney (note 5 above) para 58. 79 R v Cambridge Health Authority, ex parte B [1995] 2 All ER 129 (CA) at 137c-d, quoted in Soobramoney (note 5 above) para 52. 80 Soobramoney (note 5 above) para 53. 2 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E law dealing with the right to die,81 he concludes that ‘[c]ourts are not the proper place to resolve the agonising personal … problems that underlie these issues’82 (my emphasis) and that ‘[o]ur country’s legal system simply “cannot replace the more intimate struggle that must be borne by the patient … and those who care about the patient” ’83 (my emphasis). The message seems clear: because issues surrounding a person’s death are intensely personal, the court is powerless to address Mr Soobramoney’s plight: ‘[C]onsiderations of the wisdom and utility of the actions that might have been taken are beside the point. Normative debate [about, for instance, whether or not the balance struck ‘between the equally valid entitlements or expectations of a multitude of claimants’84 that had resulted in Mr Soobramoney being denied the treatment he required, was appropriate] is not invited.’85 Questions of death are private, not political. What makes Sachs J’s assertion of this rhetorical depoliticization strategy so startling, is that the US right to die case law he refers to so as to make his point is wholly inapposite. Certainly, when the question is whether or not the state should allow a person who does not want to live anymore to die, the issue whether or not or to what extent a court can prescribe the choice to a patient arises. But Mr Soobramoney was in the opposite position – he very much wanted to live, and the question in his case was whether or not the state is obliged to keep him alive. I fail to see how the issues that arise in determining that question are ‘agonising personal problems’ part of an ‘intimate struggle’ that Mr Soobramoney should be left to go through on his own – the essence of Mr Soobramoney’s claim is after all that the state is obliged to get involved in his life and possible death. How does one make sense of this mistaken analogy? Sachs J could have made his point relying only on the institutional capacity arguments, without having to go any further. Thomas Ross has said that ‘judges invoke the rhetoric of judicial helplessness most fervently when con- fronted with a problem of unjust and tragic dimensions’.86 Perhaps it was precisely the acutely political nature of Mr Soobramoney’s predicament – the tragic fact that his position is compared to that of others, and that the state makes a choice not to intervene in his – that prompted Sachs J to go to such tortuous lengths to justify his and the rest of the Court’s inaction. As such this element of the opinion constitutes an extraordinary flight from politics. A second example of the Constitutional Court’s domestication of needs talk occurs in Groot- boom. The Grootboom community’s claim for shelter was partly based on children’s section 28(1)(c) right to shelter. Although Yacoob J, for the Court, decided the case on the basis of the section 26(1) right of everyone to have access to adequate housing, he did provide an interpreta- tion of section 28(1)(c). The linchpin of this interpretation is a conflation of section 28(1)(c) with section 28(1)(a), which proclaims children’s right ‘to family care or parental care, or to appropri- ate alternative care when removed from the family environment’. In Yacoob J’s words: [Sections 28(1)(b) and 28(1)(c)] must be read together. They ensure that children are properly cared for by their parents or families, and that they receive appropriate alter- native care in the absence of parental or family care … Subsection (1)(b) defines those responsible for giving care while ss (1)(c) lists various aspects of the care entitlement.87 81 Cruzan v Director, Missouri Department of Health, et al 497 US 261 (1990), quoted in Soobramoney (note 5 above) para 56. 82 Soobramoney (note 5 above) para 58. 83 In re Jobes 529 A2d 434 at 451 (NJ SCt, 1987), quoted in Soobramoney (note 5 above) para 58. 84 Soobramoney (note 5 above) para 54. 85 Ross (note 17 above) at 1511. 86 Ibid. 87 Grootboom (note 6 above) para 76. On this basis Yacoob J proceeds to argue that the state has only a residual duty to provide shelter to children – the primary duty to do so rests on parents and family and the state incurs the direct duty to do so only with respect to those children ‘who are removed from their fami- lies’.88 Where children are cared for by their parents or families (are still with their parents or families) the only duty the state carries with respect to them is ‘to provide the legal and admin- istrative infrastructure necessary to ensure that children are accorded the protection contem- plated by s 28’.89 From this Yacoob J’s conclusion follows ineluctably:90 It was not contended that the children who are respondents in this case should be provided with shelter apart from their parents. Those of the respondents in this case who are children are being cared for by their parents; they are not in the care of the State, in any alternative care, or abandoned. [T]herefore, there was no obligation upon the State to provide shelter to those of the respondents who were children. Yacoob J’s interpretative maneuvering clearly ‘directs dependency away from the state [to the fam- ily] and [so] privatizes it’.91 The result is profoundly depoliticizing. It allows Yacoob J simply to ignore the social fact that often children who are ‘properly’ with their parents or family are worse of than those who find themselves in some form of alternative care, because their parents or fami- ly are simply too poor ‘properly’ to care for them. It also allows him to ignore the question whether or not the State has a duty, where children are with their parents or family but in a situation of indi- gence, to provide forms of material care directly to those children. Finally, it allows him to skirt the deeply political question whether or not, in the social provisioning activities of the state, children’s needs should enjoy material priority over the needs of others. As with Sachs J’s opinion in Soobramoney, what makes Yacoob J’s depoliticising strategy in Grootboom all the more remark- able is that it was unnecessary – Yacoob J’s interpretation of sections 28(1)(b) and (c) is certainly not the only interpretation possible, nor even the most obvious. There is no textual reason to sub- sume subsection (1)(c) into subsection (1)(b) as Yacoob J did – the various entitlements listed in the subsections of section 28(1) (there are nine – (a) to (i)) are connected to each other with an ‘and’ and seem to be intended as separate entitlements. It is also a plausible interpretation to say that sub- section (1)(b) refers to the emotional and other non-material aspects of care, whilst subsection (1)(c) lists elements of material care.92 Yacoob J had to make a conscious choice to adopt the interpreta- tion he did, it is not suggested by the text – and his employment of the depoliticizing strategy flow- ing from that interpretation was equally a conscious choice. To some extent my use of these two examples of the domestication of needs talk by the Court is gratuitous. Yacoob J’s interpretation of section 28(1)(c) in Grootboom was reversed in Treatment Action Campaign. The Court still employed Yacoob J’s view that the primary duty to provide shelter, health care, nutrition and social services rests on parents and family, with only an alternative duty falling on the State,93 but extended the circumstances under which this alternative duty would kick in. As the mothers with which the case was concerned were ‘for the most part indigent and unable to gain access to private medical treatment which is beyond their Politics of Need Interpretation 29 88 Ibid para 77. 89 Ibid para 78. 90 Ibid para 79. 91 Fineman (note 16 above) at 2205. 92 See Jooste v Botha 2002 (2) BCLR 187 (T). 93 Treatment Action Campaign (note 7 above) para 75. 3 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E means’ for them and their children, ‘[t]hey and their children are in the main dependent upon the State to make health care services available to them.’94 As a result the state incurred a duty to provide health care services to their children, even though their children were still in their care. In addition, the two instances of domestication that I relate are isolated incidents and cer- tainly cannot be used to indicate a trend. However, the depoliticizing bent of the Court is demonstrated much more clearly in Soobramoney, Grootboom and Treatment Action Cam- paign in the Court’s use of the rhetorical strategy of instrumentalisation – here a trend can be ascertained, and it is this to which I now turn. As could be expected, one of the major concerns of the Constitutional Court’s thus far in its socio-economic rights cases has been to determine the scope of its review powers with respect to socio-economic rights.95 This was particularly so in its first three cases, Soobramoney, Grootboom, and Treatment Action Campaign. In these cases the Court struggled with basic questions such as which kinds of issues that arose in socio-economic rights cases it is compe- tent to engage with at all, what its standard of scrutiny should be there where it does engage with the issues, and what the scope of its power is to provide relief there where it has exercised its review power and found a breach of a socio-economic right. What is interesting is the idiom that the Court has employed to justify the choices it has made in this respect. In its first three cases, the Court has, when engaging with the different questions relat- ed to the nature and scope of its review powers, relied in the first place on ‘institutional capacity’ arguments. That is, what motivates the Court’s decision to limit the scope of its review powers in a particular instance has been its perceived lack of the requisite technical expertise and institutional capacity properly to engage with the issues. The Court has utilized these institutional capacity argu- ments when seeking to justify its choice not to decide a particular question raised in the course of socio-economic rights litigation. In Treatment Action Campaign, for example, the Court explains its decision not to decide whether or not the State’s constitutional duties in terms of section 27(1) requires it to provide formula feed to HIV-positive mothers to prevent the transmission of HIV to their children through breast feeding by saying that this question ‘raises complex issues’ that it does not have the capacity or information on the basis of which to decide.96 The Court’s rejection of the ‘minimum core content’ approach to deciding claims for access to basic resources has equally been motivated with reference to its institutional incapacity to access and analyse the kind and quantity of information that would be required to determine what the minimum core of any given right in any given set of circumstances entails.97 Finally, the Court has justified its adoption of what it has 94 Ibid para 79. 95 As could be expected, because the debate about whether to include socio-economic rights in the 1996 Constitution (for a summary see S Liebenberg ‘Interpretation of Socio-Economic Rights’ in M Chaskalson, J Kentridge, J Klaaren, G Marcus, D Spitz, A Stein & S Woolman (eds) Constitutional Law of South Africa (2nd edition OS, December 2003) chapter 33, 3-4) was a debate about their justiciability and the proposals and counter-proposals made in this respect amounted to proposals about the manner in which courts could exercise their review powers with respect to these rights; see N Haysom ‘Constitutionalism, Majoritarian Democracy and Socio-Economic Rights’ (1992) 8 SAJHR 451; E Mureinik ‘Beyond a Charter of Luxuries: Economic Rights in the Constitution’ (1992) 8 SAJHR 464; and DM Davis ‘The Case Against the Inclusion Of Socio-Economic Demands In a Bill of Rights Except as Directive Principles’ (1992) 8 SAJHR 475. The subsequent academic debate has also focused the extent of courts’ review power with respect to socio-eco- nomic rights; see eg CR Sunstein ‘Social and Economic Rights? Lessons from South Africa’ (2001) 11:4 Constitutional Forum 123; and T Roux ‘Legitimating Transformation: Political Resource Allocation in the South African Constitutional Court’ (2003) 10 Democratization 92. 96 Treatment Action Campaign (note 7 above) para 128. 97 Grootboom (note 6 above) para 33; Treatment Action Campaign (note 7 above) para 37. called a ‘restrained role’ in reviewing State conduct in light of socio-economic rights, embodied in its ‘reasonableness review’ approach, also with reference to its institutional incapacity.98 The Court’s reliance on these institutional capacity arguments in this respect is in itself uncontroversial. Certainly the Court, when it employs this rhetoric, enters into a depoliticizing discourse – it effectively instrumentalises the questions that it is considering, describing them as ‘technical problems for managers and planners … in contradistinction to political matters.’99 However, although there is room for argument about the extent to which the Court is institu- tionally incapable in any given context,100 it cannot be denied that it is indeed institutionally constrained and that the depoliticisation that it engages in on that basis alone is to some extent inevitable. What does make the Court’s use of this particular instance of ‘instrumentalising’ rhetoric problematic, or more problematic than it would otherwise be, is not so much the fact that it defers, but what it is that it defers to. Central to the Court’s self-limitation of its powers of review and remedy in the three early cases is a second set of arguments: ‘constitutional comi- ty’ arguments. Equally as concerned as the Court is about its institutional incapacity, it is con- cerned about its institutional illegitimacy. When the Court defers, declining to decide a partic- ular issue, or to apply a stringent standard of scrutiny, or to impose an intrusive order, it defers not only to the complexity of the issues at hand, recognizing that it is incapable of deciding them. It also, more importantly, defers to, or defers in favour of the other branches of govern- ment – the executive, the legislature or the state administration – on the understanding that it is, in the context of institutional spheres of power, the inappropriate forum to decide them. In short, the problem with defining the nature and scope of its review powers for the Court ‘comes down mainly, if not solely, to a matter of separation of powers’.101 This is true in all the contexts within which the Court has had occasion to describe the lim- its and nature of its powers. In Soobramoney, Chaskalson P justifies his choice not to engage with the decisions made with respect to the rationing of health care resources that led to Mr Soobramoney’s exclusion from treatment as follows: ‘These choices involve difficult decisions [here is the reference to institutional incapacity] to be taken at the political level in fixing the health budget, and at the functional level in deciding upon the priorities to be met. [here is the deference to the other branches of government] A court will be slow to interfere with rational decisions taken in good faith by the political organs and medical authorities whose responsi- bility it is to deal with such matters’102 (my emphasis). In Grootboom Yacoob J, in describing the reasonableness review test that the Court fashioned in that case, emphasizes that ‘a court considering reasonableness will not enquire whether other more desirable or favourable meas- ures could have been adopted, or whether public money could have been better spent.’103 Politics of Need Interpretation 31 98 Treatment Action Campaign (note 7 above) para 38: ‘Courts are ill-suited to adjudicate upon issues where Court orders could have multiple social and economic consequences for the community.’ See also the Court’s justification for the lenient standard of scrutiny adopted in Soobramoney (note 5 above) para 29: ‘A court will be slow to interfere with rational decisions taken in good faith by the political organs and med- ical authorities whose responsibility it is to deal with such matters’. 99 Fraser (note 1 above) at 299. 100 It has, for example, been pointed out that the Court is in fact capable of determining the minimum core with respect to a given right, despite its protestations to the contrary, provided that it understands correct- ly what the minimum core entails; D Bilchitz ‘Giving Socio-Economic Rights Teeth: The Minimum Core and its Importance’ (2002) 118 SALJ 484 at 487. 101 FI Michelman ‘The Constitution, Social Rights, and Liberal Political Justification’ (2003) 1 International Journal of Constitutional Law 13 at 15. 102 Soobramoney (note 5 above) para 29. 103 Grootboom (note 6 above) para 41. 3 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E Instead, he proceeds, ‘[t]he precise contours and content of the measures to be adopted are pri- marily a matter for the legislature and the Executive’.104 Finally, in Treatment Action Campaign one of the primary motivations for the Court’s decision not to impose structural injunctive relief on the government is its concern that in doing so it will have to prescribe par- ticular policy and rationing choices to it, instead of determining only the contours of what is required and leaving the details of planning and implementation to government itself.105 Certainly, one might argue in favour of the Court that at the heart of its concern with the con- stitutional comity of its engagement with socio-economic rights is a concern with democracy. The Court, acutely aware of its position as the least democratically accountable branch of government, defers to the other branches, because in doing so it believes it respects the democratic will of which the political branches are the repositories.106 But the conception of democracy, or of politics or the political that underlies this concern is a peculiarly limited one. The Court’s concern with constitu- tional comity evinces what Nancy Fraser has described as an institutional understanding of politics and democracy, in terms of which ‘a matter is deemed political if it is handled directly in the insti- tutions of the official governmental system, including parliaments, administrative apparatuses, and the like’107 and in terms of which democracy occurs only within these institutions of the official governmental system. This understanding of democracy and politics stands in contrast to what Fraser describes as a discursive sense of politics, in which ‘something is “political” if it is contested across a range of different discursive arenas and among a range of different publics’ and in which democracy occurs not only in the institutions of the official governmental system, but in all of these (official and unofficial) ‘discursive arenas’ and ‘publics’. Stated differently, the Court’s stance reflects a dependent conception of democracy, according to which democracy takes place only in formally constituted democratic structures, where political questions of, for example, distribution of resources are decided for and the results presented to civil society. Again, this conception stands in contrast to a participatory model of democracy, in which the focus is on creating and maintain- ing structures for the democratic process ‘which maximize the allocation of equal political power to the citizenry’ across the board of the different (official and unofficial) discursive arenas.108 Against this background, it becomes clear that the Court’s instrumentalising rhetoric that it employs to justify its choices with respect to self-limitation of its powers operates to depoliti- cise issues of poverty, need and social provisioning of the State in two respects. First, and most obviously, the Court’s rhetoric depoliticises in that it describes the issues in question as of a technical rather than a political nature. As pointed out above, this can to some extent be seen as inevitable. However, second, the Court’s rhetoric depoliticises in that it relegates the dis- course about these issues, even in their technical sense, wholly to the formally constituted polit- ical branches of government ‘whose responsibility [and right] it is to deal with such matters’.109 104 Ibid. 105 Treatment Action Campaign (note 7 above) paras 96-114 & 129-133. 106 See Roux (note 95 above), who explores the currency that this concern with democratic legitimacy has in the Court’s conception of its review powers, and praises the Court for the extent to which it manages to remain appropriately respectful of democratic prerogatives in this respect. 107 Fraser (note 1 above). 108 Davis (note 95 above) at 488-489. See also E Pieterse & M van Donk ‘The Politics of Socio-Economic Rights in South Africa. Ten Years after Apartheid’ (2004) 5:5 ESR Review 12 at 13: ‘The realisation of socio-economic rights is an inherently political process, which needs to involve rights-holders … in deter- mining the desired outcomes, objectives, strategies and acceptable trade-offs so that they are enabled to take control of their own destinies. This inevitably implies a political process of negotiation, disagreement, con- flict, occasionally consensus, and, at a minimum, forms of mutual accommodation.’ 109 Soobramoney (note 5 above) para 29. The message to those other, unofficial ‘publics’ (social movements, NGO’s, ordinary people) who operate democratically in those other, unofficial ‘discursive arenas’ is therefore not only that the issues that they deal with are difficult ones in a technical sense, requiring of them sus- tained, informed engagement110 which they, like the Court, might not have the capacity for. It is also that the issues are, as with the Court, simply not their business. The Court’s rhetoric casts them not as active participants in the process of interpretation of their needs, engaged in polit- ical action, but as the passive recipients of services – their needs, predefined by the political branches of government, are administered to them through a process of therapeutic assis- tance.111 (C) KHOSA, MODDERKLIP AND PE MUNICIPALITY: TOWARD A DISCURSIVE UNDERSTANDING OF DEMOCRACY? In socio-economic rights decisions of the Constitutional Court and the Supreme Court of Appeal subsequent to Soobramoney, Grootboom and Treatment Action Campaign it is possi- ble to see the beginnings of a countervailing trend in the Court’s rhetoric that is more closely allied to a discursive or participatory conception of politics and democracy and that can in this respect be contrasted to the Constitutional Court’s instrumentalising rhetoric in the earlier three cases. In the first place, in the cases in question (Khosa, Modderklip and PE Municipality) the Constitutional Court and Supreme Court of Appeal have emphasised the political agency of the poor people involved vis-à-vis government by taking its operation into account in interpreting the rights in question. In Khosa Mokgoro J, for example, in finding that the State had a consti- tutional duty to provide social assistance to indigent (non-citizen) permanent residents in South Africa, placed great stock in the fact that permanent residents had through their conduct in effect thrown in their lot with South Africa. In this respect Mokgoro J points out that permanent res- idents intend to become South African citizens, that they have made their homes here and have brought their families here, that for many their children have been born here, that they owe a duty of allegiance to the State112 and that they pay taxes in South Africa.113 As a result, although not yet formally citizens, they have claimed their membership of our community through the exercise of their political agency and deserve to be treated equally as fully fledged such mem- bers.114 In Modderklip Harms J for the Supreme Court of Appeal equally emphasizes the role of the political agency of the property owner and the squatters in determining the resolution of the case. In this respect Harms J points out that the landowner had at all times acted within the law and had throughout sought to effect an amicable solution that would vindicate both his and the squatters’ rights115 and that the squatters had occupied the land without intending to force the hand of the state to provide them with land in preference to others and had also sought to reach an amicable solution both with the landowner and the state.116 These indications of an attitude of political engagement with each other and with the State play an important role in eventually Politics of Need Interpretation 33 110 Wilson (note 41 above) at 447. 111 Habermas (note 25 above) at 210; see also Fraser (note 1 above) at 307. 112 Khosa (note 8 above) para 59. 113 Ibid para 74. 114 Ibid. 115 Modderklip (note 10 above) paras 33, 37 & 38. 116 Ibid para 25. 3 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E persuading the Court to find in favour of both the landowner and the squatters against the State, who by contrast had failed diligently to pursue a settlement and had reneged on agreements reached,117 despite the fact that it had itself caused the predicament of the squatters and the landowner by previously evicting the squatters from state land without providing alternative accommodation.118 Similarly, in PE Municipality, the Constitutional Court emphasises the polit- ical agency of the group of squatters that the State sought to evict there. Again the fact that they had occupied the land in question not in order to force the municipality to provide to them, in preference to others, alternative land when they are eventually evicted, but because they had been evicted from elsewhere and had nowhere else to go119 and that they had attempted to negotiate with the property owners and the State whilst the municipality had made no serious effort to reach an amicable conclusion to the matter, but had rushed to apply for an eviction order and had acted unilaterally,120 partly drove the Court to the conclusion that an eviction order could not be granted unless suitable alternative land or accommodation was provided. Indeed, in PE Municipality these factors, together with others, were seen as so important that the Court took the surprisingly intrusive step of rejecting the municipality’s offer of two possible alternative sites, finding that they were not suitable to the squatters’ needs. Certainly one has to sound a note of caution here. As with any form of community-oriented rhetoric, the Court’s emphasis in these three cases on the ‘proper’ political action of the per- manent residents, the property owner and the squatters runs the risk of being read in an exclu- sionary fashion. So, for example, Mokgoro J explicitly uses this rhetoric to distinguish perma- nent residents from other non-citizens in South Africa and then, on the basis of that distinction to deny other non-citizens membership of the South African community.121 Equally, the two courts’ reference in both Modderklip and PE Municipality to the fact that the squatters in ques- tion had occupied land illegally not with the intention to ‘jump’ the housing queue by forcing government to provide them with alternative accommodation when they were evicted, effec- tively marks the conduct of squatters who have indeed acted with that purpose as ‘improper’ and excludes their conduct (certainly equally born of desperation) from the realm of ‘proper’ political action. In this respect the two courts run the risk of creating an idea of acceptable civic action that one has to comply with in order to form part of the South African political com- munity, excluding other forms of political action.122 Nevertheless, this aspect of the cases is important because at least it casts the permanent residents, property owner and squatters in the role of political actors, actively (and legitimately) engaging in the interpretation of their needs together with the State, who is in turn cast as just one more (albeit particularly authoritative) such participant in the process of need interpretation. In this way it avoids the depoliticising instrumentalist effect of the Constitutional Court’s earlier separation of powers rhetoric. This new concern with participatory democracy and discursive politics shows also in the manner in which the Constitutional Court and the Supreme Court of Appeal exercised and described their remedial powers in the three later cases. This is evident first in Modderklip. Modderklip was presented by the State as an intractable situation. The State argued that it 117 Ibid paras 35-38. 118 Ibid para 35. 119 PE Municipality (note 9 above) paras 49 & 55. 120 Ibid paras 45, 55-57 & 59. 121 Khosa (note 8 above) para 59: ‘For these reasons, I exclude temporary residents …’. 122 See in this respect K van Marle ‘Love, Law and the South African Community: Critical Reflections on “Suspect Intimacies” and “Immanent Subjectivity”’ in H Botha, AJ van der Walt & JWG van der Walt Rights and Democracy in a Transformative Constitution (2004) 231 at 245-246. could not enforce Modderklip’s eviction order against the squatters, because it did not have the resources to do so, particularly as it would have to provide alternative land to the squatters were it to evict them.123 This it would not be able to do also because it did not have the req- uisite resources, but, more importantly, because to provide the squatters with alternative land would allow them to jump the housing queue, thus legitimating unacceptable social behav- iour.124 This stance of the State’s is a particularly clear example of the strategy of naturalisa- tion referred to above: The State throws its hands in the air, overwhelmed by the intractable nature of the problems facing it and so attempts to remove the issues in question from the arena of political contestation. Harms J is unambiguous in his rejection of this strategy. Holding that ‘Courts [and by implication the State] should not be overawed by practical problems’ but should instead ‘mould an order that will provide effective relief to those affected by a constitu- tional breach’125 he proceeds to find a solution where the State said there was none, ordering the State to pay damages to the property owner and to allow the squatters to remain on the land in question until alternative accommodation is found. Harmse J’s ‘can do’ rhetoric pow- erfully counteracts the State’s attempts at depoliticisation and places the kinds of issues that were dealt with in the case (homelessness, land invasion and eviction) squarely back in the domain of political contestation. In addition, because it amounted to the implementation of a proposal that both the property owner and the squatters had made in the course of their attempted negotiations with the State,126 it emphasises the involvement of these non-official political actors in the process of defining their needs and finding ways to satisfy them. As such, it underscores a participatory understanding of democracy and a discursive understanding of politics and counteracts the idea that it is only the State who can engage politically with the issues and then hand down solutions from on high. The repoliticising trend continues in the Constitutional Court’s description of its remedial powers in PE Municipality. Both Grootboom and Treatment Action Campaign have been criti- cised for the Court’s failure to employ structural injunctive relief. In Grootboom, the Court issued a simple declaratory order, leaving the remedy of the constitutional defect in its housing programme entirely to the state.127 In Treatment Action Campaign, the Court similarly issued a declarator, coupled with a mandatory order requiring the state to remedy the constitutional defect in its programme for prevention of MTCT of HIV.128 However, despite confirming that it did indeed have the power to do so, the Court again declined to issue a supervisory interdict, holding that there was no indication that the state would not implement its order properly.129 The critiques of the two cases in this respect have focused on the extent to which the failure to employ such structural relief trenched on the effectiveness of the Court’s remedies.130 However, Dennis Davis has recently instead emphasised the role of such structural relief in promoting dem- ocratic accountability. To him, the failure of the Court to employ structural relief has caused it to miss an opportunity to allow those affected by its judgements to be involved in their imple- mentation as active political agents and as such has undermined the idea of participatory democ- Politics of Need Interpretation 35 123 Modderklip (note 10 above) para 13. 124 Ibid para 29. 125 Ibid para 42. 126 Ibid para 14. 127 Grootboom (note 6 above) para 99. 128 Treatment Action Campaign (note 7 above) para 135. 129 Ibid para 129. 130 See eg K Pillay ‘Implementation of Grootboom: Implications for the Enforcement of Socio-Economic Rights’ (2002) 6 Law, Democracy and Development 255. 3 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E racy.131 In PE Municipality Sachs J seems to heed this call. Although in the event declining to do so,132 Sachs J raises the possibility that a court, in providing a remedy in an eviction case such as the one the Constitutional Court was faced with could order compulsory mediation between the parties. That is, a court could make a normative finding, in the sense of describing the out- comes that the constitutional and other legal duties at play in the case required, but could then order the parties to enter into a process of mediation in order to agree upon the most appropri- ate means with which to reach those outcomes.133 As Charles Sable and William Simon have pointed out,134 this kind of ‘experimentalist’135 structural injunctive relief combines the virtues of the Court requiring constitutional duties to be met in a practically effective way, whilst re- maining respectful of its own institutional incapacity with respect to the substantive issues involved in the implementation of its normative findings. For my purposes it shows a further important virtue. Courts employing such relief would certainly, as Sable and Simon argue, remain appropriately respectful of their own institutional incapacity by deferring to another forum than themselves with respect to the implementation of their orders. However, they will defer in this respect not in favour of the political branches of government only, as the Con- stitutional Court has been wont to do, but to the political process in the wider, discursive sense of the word outlined above. In this way courts would be able to subvert the instrumentalising rhetoric that they seem inevitably to have to engage in when adjudicating socio-economic rights claims and give effect to a participatory, rather than institutional understanding of democracy. IV Conclusion At the outset of this paper I recalled Karl Klare’s challenge to judges and lawyers: In order to give expression to the transformative ethos of the Constitution, they should attempt to work in such a way as to deepen democratic culture in South Africa. I then proceeded to discuss one way in which courts can do so – by avoiding in their socio-economic rights judgements the use and consequent confirmation of rhetorical strategies of depoliticisation commonly used in the political discourse around the interpretation of need and poverty. I pointed to various instances in which courts have used and so confirmed some of these strategies, but also detailed instances in which they subverted these processes of depoliticisation. The countervailing tendencies that I identified, although important, of course do not allow courts to escape or to mediate the ten- sions between rights and democracy that their work is inevitably caught up in – judges contin- ue to operate under freedom and constraint, their work inevitably both guarantees and denies freedom, reinforces and destructs democracy. Nevertheless, the Supreme Court of Appeal and Constitutional Court’s rehabilitation of discursive politics through its emphasis on political agency and use of inventive remedies in Khosa, Modderklip and PE Municipality constitutes an important moment in the ‘deepening of democracy’ that Klare requires. 131 DM Davis ‘Socio-Economic Rights in South Africa. The Record of the Constitutional Court after Ten Years’ (2004) 5:5 ESR Review 3 at 6-7. 132 PE Municipality (note 9 above) para 47. 133 Ibid para 39-46. 134 CF Sable & WH Simon ‘Destabilisation Rights: How Public Law Litigation Succeeds’ (2004) 117 Harvard LR 1016 at 1019 & 1053-1056. 135 As opposed to ‘command-and-control’ injunctive regulation; ibid 1019. New Tools for the Constitutional Bench S TA N A D U P L E S S I S 1 Associate Professor, Department of Economics, Stellenbosch University ‘… on those occasions when the legal process does establish that an infringement on an entrenched right has occurred… The courts have a particular responsibility in this regard and are obliged to “forge new tools” and shape innovative remedies, if needs be, to achieve this goal.’2 I Introduction It is highly unlikely that Justice Ackerman referred to positive theories of social change when he called on courts in South Africa to forge new tools in their rights jurisprudence, but I will argue here that such an allusion would not have been amiss. Indeed, such tools are indispensa- ble for a Constitutional Court seeking the realisation of social and economic rights3 as is the case in South Africa. 4 Though the argument of this chapter is formal, the intention is practical and constructed specifically to participate in the present debate on social and economic rights in South Africa. In short, I argue that a constitutional court such as South Africa’s might have to acquire and use explicitly the tools of positive social science – notably of economics – to complement the normative and legal tools already at its disposal. Since the Constitutional Court is already applying social science implicitly, to the extent that it regards social and economic rights as par- tially justiciable, it would be advantageous not only academically, but even more so practical- 1 I wish to thank Ronelle Burger for helpful comments, Gerhard du Plessis for his help with the jurisprudence literature, Gerhard du Toit for considerable help with editing and Thinus Keefe for research assistance. The usual disclaimer applies. 2 Justice Ackerman for the South African Constitutional Court in Fose v Minister of Safety and Security 1997 (3) SA 786 (CC) para 69 (fn omitted). 3 The following sections of the South African Constitution pertain to social and economic rights: section 25(5) (the right to equitable access to land); section 26(1) (the right to adequate housing); section 27(1) (the right of access to health care, adequate food and water and social security and social assistance) and section 28(1) (the right of children to adequate food, shelter, health care and social services). This list is from A J van der Walt ‘A South African Reading of Frank Michelman’s Theory of Social Justice’ in H Botha, AJ van der Walt and J van der Walt (eds) Rights and Democracy in a Transformative Constitution (2003) 163 fn 5. 4 Justice Moseneke argued along similar lines: ‘The Constitution has reconfigured the way judges should do their work. It invites us into a new plane of jurisprudential creativity and self-reflection about legal method, analysis and reasoning consistent with its transformative roles’; see D Moseneke ‘The Fourth Bram Fischer Memorial Lecture: Transformative Adjudication’ (2002) 17 SAJHR 309 at 318. This volume explores var- ious theoretical perspectives on Moseneke’s ‘new plane of jurisprudential creativity’. The intention of this chapter is to broaden this theoretical discussion beyond jurisprudence, as the wide-ranging scope of social and political rights calls the Justices of the Constitutional Court beyond the reach of jurisprudence. 3 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E ly, if the social science of the Constitutional Court was explicit, open to scrutiny and, in that way, open to the possibility of improvement through critical discussion. The first section of this chapter develops an argument for the use of positive theory by the Constitutional Court and contrasts such a theory with normative and legal theories of social and economic rights. However, to assist the practical deliberations of the Constitutional Court requires not only a case for positive theory, but an argument for a specific positive theory. To inform that choice the broad range of such theories is sketched in section III. The fourth section narrows the discussion to one particular theory, the so-called New Institutional Economics, which is a positive theory of the requisite kind and which is gaining widespread theoretical and empirical support in economics. Section V demonstrates how the New Institutional Economics could be used to inform the analysis and enforcement of social and economic rights in South Africa and how the use of such a positive theory often complements the other theoretical perspectives. II Why the Constitutional Court should use Theories of Positive Social Science The explicit provision of social and economic rights in the Bill of Rights and various other arti- cles of South Africa’s 1996 Constitution is widely noted and often applauded.5 South African legal scholars have argued (in this volume and elsewhere) that these rights are justiciable in a comparable manner to the civil and political rights (sometimes called ‘first generation rights’) in the Constitution. This interpretation has found support in the Constitutional Court, where it has been argued that social and economic rights are ‘…at least to some extent, justiciable’.6 The project on ‘Theories of Social Justice’ that gave rise to this volume takes the above as given. In South Africa this understanding of justiciable social and economic rights have to be seen in the context of a developing country with deep poverty combined with unequal access to resources and opportunities that are to a considerable extent due to historical discrimination. Reading the argu- ments for justiciable social and economic rights in the light of these economic and social challenges facing contemporary South Africa resulted in the two hypotheses that informed this project. The first hypothesis is that ‘theory matters’, since theory is likely to influence the jurispru- dence of social and economic rights in South Africa, as elsewhere. The second hypothesis is that ‘theoretical drag’, or the possibility that theory that lagged behind the drive for transformation in South Africa and that theory might, in this way, be delaying material improvement for the most vulnerable sections of the South African population. Against this background, Justice Ackerman’s call for ‘new tools’ (quoted above) is here understood to mean, inter alia, solutions to theoretical drag in the implementation of social and economic rights. It is easy to conceive how theory might matter and to agree that theoretical drag should be avoided, but it is harder to discern the kind(s) of theory that is required. At this point the com- mon ground between the legal and economic literature seems particularly barren, with econo- mists emphasising sustained economic growth as a (perhaps the most) important factor in the progressive realisation of social and economic rights and proposing positive theories of social change to that end. I did not detect a comparable concern with positive theories of social change 5 For example CA Sunstein ‘Social and Economic Rights? Lessons from South Africa’ (2001) Chicago Law and Economics Working Paper no 124 at 4. 6 Ex Parte Chairperson of the Constitutional Assembly 1996 (4) SA 744 (CC) para 78. in the legal literature on social and economic rights in South Africa. 7 Instead the latter contains a rich discussion of normative and legal theories underpinning social and economic rights, some of which have been repeated and extended in this volume. While legal scholars have apparent- ly been concerned with theoretical drag in jurisprudence or ethics, economists have typically been concerned with the possibility of positive theoretical drag. In the service of clarity it might be useful to state explicitly what an economist understands by the distinction between normative and legal theories of social and economic rights on the one hand and positive theories of social change on the other. In this chapter a positive theory of social change is understood to mean a set of arguments (with empirical content) referring to certain changes in society.8 Empirical content is central to that definition and is understood in the critical or Popperian tradition, that is: the empirical content of a theory is provided by potential falsification. Theories with high empirical content make bold statements about the world, and indeed it is the wide range of conceivable experience that might refute such theories that constitute their empirical content. In contrast, theories with low empirical content do not make statements at odds with possible experience.9 An example of a (highly specific) positive theory relevant to the topic under consideration is: rural South Africans would experience a sus- tained rise in average household income if the South African Constitutional Court enjoined the government to implement a basic income grant. A normative theory is here understood to be a set of arguments about the desired relation- ships and/or behaviour between persons, or between persons and their environment (whether the material environment or a spiritual dimension). Whether observed behaviour is presently or conceivably at odds with the normative recommendation does not pose an insurmountable intellectual challenge to normative theories. A relevant example of such a normative theory is: South Africans should support the implementation of the Constitution produced by a demo- cratically representative Constitutional Assembly. Finally, a legal theory is a set of arguments about the nature of the law, acceptable interpretation of the law, or the rights and obligations which derive from the law. Legal theories build on a wide range of principles, of which some are particular to jurisprudence, while others overlap with ethics or even political theory. Liebenberg provides the following summary of an envisaged jurisprudence relevant to justiciable social and economic rights: ‘The jurisprudence will define the nature of the state’s obligations in relation to socio-economic rights, the conditions under which these rights can be claimed, and the nature of the relief that those who turn to the courts can expect’.10 Evidently, the consideration that ‘theory matters’ requires a preliminary answer to the ques- tion: ‘what sort of theory’? If we restrict our attention for the time being to positive theories, then the questions arises: What arguments could be used to evaluate the hypothesis that ‘positive the- ory matters’ for the jurisprudence of social and economic rights? Perhaps it is easiest to answer New Tools for the Constitutional Bench 39 7 This is a vast and rapidly expanding literature, which is the despair of a non-specialist. There is a small over- lap between the legal and economic disciplines domestically but the interdisciplinary discussion has been hampered by a sometimes overly rigid approach to the rights literature on the side of economists and a sometimes overly ideological approach on the side of legal scholars to what has been called neo-liberal eco- nomics. 8 Economists often insist that positive theory of this kind is value neutral; see RA Posner ‘Values and Consequences: An Introduction to Economic Analysis of Law’ (1998) Chicago Law & Economics Working Paper no 53 at 3. 9 For an elaboration of these views see for example KR Popper The Logic of Science (1959) at 41. 10 S Liebenberg ‘South Africa’s Evolving Jurisprudence on Socio-Economic Rights: An Effective Tool in Challenging Poverty?’ (2002) 6 Law, Democracy and Development 159 at 160. 4 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E this question in the negative, that is, to demonstrate the consequences of proceeding with the judicial implementation of social and economic rights without considering positive theory. Two subdivisions of the academic literature in economics is highly relevant in this regard. First, the public choice literature provides ample theoretical and empirical reasons for doubting that the outcomes of (especially ambitious) social plans will necessarily match their inten- tions.11 Second, the development economic literature has analysed decades of disappointment with development plans.12 Giving particular content to ‘social transformation’ in South Africa is undoubtedly con- tentious,13 though it almost certainly entails a dimension of economic development. We are not only interested in equitable participation in the economy this year but also, and perhaps more so, we are interested in a sustained rise of the average income and in effective and sustained poverty alleviation. Such changes would be transforming in an economy that has known decades of stagnation and exclusion. The record of frustrated development, especially in Africa, Latin America and South Asia, has provided important refutations of various positive theories of economic development.14 The Constitutional Court could guard against a repetition of similar mistakes by learning the negative lessons of these positive theories. A similar argument could be made for learning the negative lessons recorded in the pub- lic choice literature. In the context of a discussion about the Constitutional Court’s role in the transformation of society (via the interpretation and implementation of social and eco- nomic rights) it seems reasonable to assume that at least the behaviour of the Constitutional Court, but also that of government at all levels, has to be analysed. Most notably, any uncritical belief in the efficiency of government has to be tempered by the public choice analysis of ‘government failures’. Indeed, the public choice literature has undermined the 11 See for example: V Tanzi ‘The Changing Role of the State in the Economy’ (1997) IMF Working Paper WP/97/114 passim; JM Buchanan ‘Politics without Romance’ in JM Buchanan (ed) The Collected Works of James Buchanan. Volume I. The Logical Foundations of Constitutional Liberty (1999) 45; JM Buchanan & RA Musgrave Public Finance and Public Choice. Two Contrasting Visions of the State (2000) passim; V Tanzi ‘The Role of the State and the Quality of the Public Sector’ (2000) IMF Working Paper WP/00/36) passim. 12 See for example P Collier & JW Gunning ‘Explaining African Economic Performance’ (1999) 37 Journal of Economic Literature 64-111; W Easterly The Elusive Quest for Growth (2001) at 23. 13 Moseneke (note 4 above) at 315 quotes Albertyn & Goldblatt approvingly where they argued that trans- formation requires ‘…a complete reconstruction of the state and society…’. It is very difficult and perhaps impossible to pursue such a comprehensive vision with the tools of positive theory as is argued below and also by KR Popper The Poverty of Historicism (1961) at 69; KR Popper ‘Towards a Rational Theory of Tradition’ in KR Popper (ed) Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge (1992) 120 at 131. An example of the sober view presently ascendant in development economics is Easterly’s conclu- sion that: ‘the problem of making poor countries rich was more difficult than we thought…[and] the rec- ommendations I have given are themselves no panacea – they will take patient incremental work and fur- ther money to implement’: Easterly (note 12 above) at 291. If we take the contextuality of all social relationships and hence all social science seriously, it precludes the possibility of discussing social relations in an as yet unknown society. We are left only with the possi- bility of piecemeal social policy - adjusting for specific problems here and there - and then learning from our mistakes as the unintended consequences of the policies unfold: Popper (note 13 above) at 70. Arguments such as these explain much of the scepticism of Utopian schemes for social reform in economics and other positive social sciences, while such systematic visions of a better tomorrow might remain useful in a differ- ent theoretical setting. 14 The failure of foreign aid to boost economic growth and development in much of the developing world is an important example discussed in, for example, Easterly (note 12 above) at 43. presumption that a centralised solution exists for every decentralised failure in society.15 Returning to justiciable social and economic rights: the Constitutional Court could avoid a repetition of the unfortunate government failures of the last fifty years by learning the lessons of the positive theories of public choice with respect to the scope and limit for action by (i) the Constitutional Court itself, (ii) the national executive, and (iii) local government. While the lessons from public choice and development economics mentioned in the last few paragraph have been essentially negative, there are also constructive reasons for recommending closer attention to positive theories of social change by the Constitutional Court. Assuming that the Constitutional Court wishes to contribute to particular changes in South African society, it stands to reason that the Court would need theories of how these changes might in reality occur. Furthermore, these theories must neither be restricted to the legal theories that inform the legit- imate scope for their action, nor must it be restricted to moral theories of what goals and pri- orities the Constitutional Court ought to be pursuing. Rather, the Constitutional Court has a need to understand whether – and if, then how – the intended consequences of a particular project are likely to arise and, perhaps more importantly, what the unintended consequences of the initiative might be. Such a focus on unintended conse- quences – and hence on the behavioural implications of incentives created by programmes under review – is central to the economic analysis of law which has gained credence in recent years.16 If positive theories of social science matter for social and economic rights, then it follows that ‘theoretical drag’ with respect to such positive theories might also hamper progress on the real- isation of these rights. Accepting the case for a positive theory does not, however, determine the particular positive theory that should be used. The next section considers a range of positive theories relevant to the questions of transformation, economic development and social and eco- nomic rights. III A Spectrum of Positive Theories The eagerly anticipated social transformation of South African society implies changes along two dimensions. The first dimension is economic growth and the economic development of society and the second dimension the degree of equality in the distribution of income and wealth. This project is concerned with the role of rights, notably social and economic rights, in the changes along these two dimensions. In the previous section it was argued that positive theory was important in understanding the role that rights could play in this transformation. Economics is one of the social sciences that offers such positive theories of social change. Economists study decisions and the constraints on these decisions and it is therefore unsurprising that economic theory could provide a useful tool to analyse the role of rights in social change. But there is a broad range of positive theories about social change, and legal scholars and the Constitutional Court will face the difficult task of judging the relative merits of these theories in order to form a rational expectation of how social and economic rights might be connected with actual social change. For the sake of analytical tractability two extreme views are presented here, though the work of leading theorists and econometricians are invariably more subtle, combining elements of New Tools for the Constitutional Bench 41 15 For an elaboration on the theory and support for public choice theory see for example Buchanan (note 11 above). 16 Posner (note 8 above) at 3. 4 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E both. The two ends of the spectrum are the decentralised theories of social change on the one hand and the centralised theories on the other.17 Centralised theories of social change are built around the vision of a centralised authority (usually the state) which takes the initiative and plays a leading role in the process of initiating and sustaining economic development. The theory of a developmental state (developed to explain the experience of notably Japan) is amongst the better known examples of this type, but this end of the spectrum reaches all the way to various forms of socialism. The intuitive appeal of the centralised theories are that they seem rational (at least in the sense of ‘rational planning’) and simple as the main requirements are apparently (i) sufficient resources and (ii) the legiti- mate authority to use these resources for the development plan. This simplicity improves trans- parency with the benefit of raising potential accountability for the planning authority. Centralised theories of social change are relevant to the implementation of social and eco- nomic rights in two ways: first by the sometimes tacit assumption that combination of suffi- cient authority and sufficient resources would very likely lead to the desired social change; and second by various empirically testable hypotheses that can be deduced from the last century of centralised attempts at social change. Though the former of these is empirically empty, the lat- ter is not and economists have checked its empirical record against expectations, with the sober- ing result summarised by Tanzi: …We now have the reality of several decades of expanded state intervention so that expectations can be compared against the results. The results from this experience have been disappointing in many countries, especially in developing countries. There is now ample evidence that large state intervention has not improved the allocation of resources, has not promoted faster growth, has not brought about a better distri- bution of income, and has not provided a more stable economic environment… .18 Despite their leading role in the development of centralised theories of change, economists have also developed decentralised theories of social change dating back to the Scottish Enlight- enment. Since then economists have theorised about the combination of institutions that would yield a peaceful and progressive social order, without making exaggerated assumptions about the moral stature of the citizens or the skill and integrity of the authorities. It was a great dis- covery of the Scottish Enlightenment that a spontaneous social order, and not unavoidable chaos, could obtain in these circumstances.19 A decentralised economy works by allowing individuals to specialise on own initiative and then to provide for the remainder of their needs through exchange. However, decentralised 17 Neither of these theories can be associated with conservative or progressive views of social change as such. In a decentralised society social change can be rapid or slow, progressive or regressive, depending on the scope for decisions by individuals and the decisions they actually make. Likewise, a centralised society might experience progressive or regressive change, and this at a rapid or slow pace, depending on the scope and capacity of government, and the actual decisions taken by authorities. The point is not that economists are agnostic about the likelihood of (say) rapid progressive change in a society (more about that in section IV) but that neither of these theoretical extremes imply a particular type of change as such. 18 Tanzi (note 11 above) at 15. 19 The self-regulated order of a decentralised society has variously been called a ‘spontaneous order’: FA Hayek ‘Individualism: True and False’ in FA Hayek (ed) Individualism and Economic Order (1984) 1 at 7; ‘ordered anarchy’: Buchanan note 11 above or the ‘invisible-hand order’ (by Nozick). The common intuition in these terms is that the social order is not the result of conscious effort by any of its constituent parts. order requires, at a minimum, secure property rights and an extravagant amount of informa- tion. It was not in the tradition of the Scottish Enlightenment to solve this problem of infor- mation by assuming ‘perfect’ knowledge either for individuals or for some social planner. Rather, the emphasis was on people’s epistemological limitations. For Hayek, this modest view of human capacity, or what he calls the ‘…constitutional limitations of man’s knowledge and interests, the fact that he cannot know more than a tiny part of the whole society and that there- fore all that can enter into his motives are the immediate effects which his actions will have in the sphere he knows…’ is central to the solution suggested by Adam Smith and others.20 It is the price mechanism which, in a competitive market, solves this information problem to a satisfactory extent and provides the incentives for using that information. 21 On this view ‘the market’ is the institutional framework, or network of links, within which voluntary exchange manifests itself. Competition is the means by which information is acquired and disseminated along this network, creating in Hayek’s words: ‘…the unity and coherence of the economic sys- tem which we presuppose when we think of it as one market.’22 Notwithstanding the power of this demonstration, it is – as described – only ‘half a theory’. The efficacy of the price system to bring about spontaneous social order is conditional on the gains of specialisation and trade exceeding the costs of trade, and this cannot be assumed. Indeed, for much of history and in most societies, the cost of trading was exceedingly high and prevented the transition to modern decentralised production. The New Institutional Economists, especially Douglass North, have suggested that it is the political and economic institutions (as defined below) in an economy that form the link between the theory of production (by speciali- sation and exchange) and transaction costs that limit the extent of the market.23 This decentralised theory of society, anchored in the vision of material progress through spe- cialisation and trade yields, empirically testable hypotheses about social change that can be test- ed with the data of the last two centuries. Of further interest to this particular project is that constitutions and the rights they define, protect and implement, play a crucial role in the decen- tralised theories of social change. In this way the decentralised theory offers an empirically testable tool for assessing the manner in which to realise, inter alia, social and economic rights. With the benefit of hindsight, economists have come to judge decentralised theories of social change more favourably than centralised theories. This was an important consideration in my decision to focus on one of the decentralised theories of social change in the following section. The analytical scope in New Institutional Economics for analysing the role of rights was a fur- ther reason. New Tools for the Constitutional Bench 43 20 Hayek ‘Individualism’ (note 19 above) at 14. 21 Towards the end of his career Paul Samuelson tried to capture what economists had learnt from the lengthy debate between proponents of decentralised development and those who argued for the ‘feasibility of social- ist rational pricing’ and his conclusion was both gracious (to Hayek, a long standing academic opponent) and modest (in its claims for the decentralised system). ‘Hayek has been persuasive,’ Samuelson admitted ‘…in arguing that experience suggests that only with heavy dependence on market pricing mechanisms can there be realised quasi-efficient and quasi-progressive organisation of societies involving humans as Darwinian history has bequeathed them’: PA Samuelson ‘Some Uneasiness with the Coase Theorem’ (1993) 7 Japan and the World Economy 1 at 7. Efficiency (in the ultimate sense) never obtains, neither in the decen- tralised systems of present day market economies, nor in the unlamented socialist experiments of the twen- tieth century. 22 FA Hayek ‘The Meaning of Competition’ in FA Hayek (ed) Individualism and Economic Order (1984) 92 at 106. 23 DC North ‘Institutions’ (1991) 5 Journal of Economic Perspectives 97 at 102; DC North Institutions, Institutional Change, and Economic Performance (1990) at 27. 4 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E IV New Institutional Economics The vast differences in standard of living – however measured – between the richest and the poorest countries in the world today is mainly a result of differences in sustained economic growth over the last millennium, with a widening of the gap since the industrial revolution.24 Economists have shown that such differences cannot, in the words of Mancur Olson ‘… be explained by differences in the ratio of population to land or natural resources, or by differ- ences in the quality of marketable human capital or personal culture…’.25 ‘The real secret of successful development is the performance of the people concerned,’ as David Landes wrote ‘…but achievement must come from within…’.26 In other words, the social change that is affected by economic development requires a certain kind of society; develop- ment requires a society where many (perhaps most) people can envisage a better future, not only for themselves, but especially for their children. But here is the crux: the path to this bet- ter future must pass through production, not predation; making new wealth, not merely divert- ing wealth from others.27 In such a society people change their behaviour, invest in their own human capital, change the size of their families and invest in the human capital of their chil- dren.28 It is this investment in human capital that unlocks the tremendous latent potential of hither- to poor societies, allowing them to experience catch-up growth as they apply the more recent vintages of knowledge and technology available in a globalising international economy. These technologies can be implemented in local conditions with the logic of trial and error, where potential return rewards risks taken and mistakes are eliminated by the material sanction of the market.29 The process of development described above has an explicit time dimension. Economic devel- opment requires more than the efficient allocation of resources in every period, it requires addi- tionally what North has called ‘adaptive efficiency’; in his words: …[adaptive efficiency] is concerned with the tolerance of a society to the acquisition of knowledge and learning; to a society’s encouragement of innovation, risk-taking, and creative activities of all sorts. The encouragement, via the appropriate institu- tional framework, of trials, experiments, and innovation, is essential because in a world of uncertainty no one knows the ‘correct’ answer to the problems we con- front… .30 24 A Maddison The World Economy: A Millennial Perspective (2002) passim; D Landes The Unbound Prometheus: Technological Change and Industrial Development in Western Europe from 1750 to the Present (2003) passim. 25 M Olson ‘Big Bills left on the Sidewalk: Why Some Nations are Rich, and Others Poor’ in S Knack (ed) Democracy, Governance and Growth (2003) 29 at 47. 26 D Landes The Wealth and Poverty of Nations. Why Some are so Rich and Some so Poor (1998) at 562. 27 S Knack ‘Predation of Production? The Impact of Political, Legal and Social Institutions’ in S Knack (ed) Democracy, Governance and Growth (2003) 1 at 1. 28 RJ Lucas Lectures on Growth Theory (2002) at v. 29 J Diamond Guns, Germs and Steel. The Fates of Human Societies (1997) passim; Landes (note 26 above) passim. 30 DC North ‘On the Economic Role of the State: Comment’ in A Heertje (ed) The Economic Role of the State (1989) 107 at 109. The concept of institutions has become central to economists’ understanding of this dynamic process of change. Formally, institutions are ‘…a set of constraints on behaviour in the form of rules and regulations; a set of procedures to detect deviations from the rules and regulations; and, finally, a set of moral, ethical behavioural norms which define the contours that constrain the way in which the rules and regulations are specified and enforcement is carried out….’,31 or in game-theoretic terms, the institutions are the ‘rules of the game’ of social interaction.32 Institutions can lower transaction costs, thereby facilitating specialisation and exchange, by rendering behaviour more stable and predictable, or in the words of Kasper and Streit: ‘…the key function of institutions is to facilitate order: a systematic, non-random and therefore com- prehensible pattern of actions and events…’.33 Institutions play this central role in the social order, since it is the combination of the formal and informal institutions with the standard con- straints of economics that ‘define the opportunity set of the economy’, as North argued else- where.34 A complex network of institutions – called the institutional matrix – facilitates all social interaction. This matrix is composed of both formal rules (for example the legal code) and informal rules (for example customs and taboos) and is both political (for example proportional representation as a voting rule) and economic (for example tariffs). This institutional matrix, including the formal rules set by government, and the informal rules that command broad adherence create and direct incentives either for productive activity or for rent seeking. Every society offers incentives for both productive activity and rent seek- ing, but economic historians such as North and development economists such as Easterly have argued that the relative weight taken by these two broad groups of incentives are a crucial fac- tor in the long run prosperity of a society.35 ‘People respond to incentives’, as William Easterly36 reminded us of the lesson of elementary economics, and that is the reason why the institutional matrix has such a profound effect on the dynamic efficiency of a society. This effect is mediated through the structure of industrial organisation encouraged, governance in the private and public sector, and flexibility in both public and private sectors.37 North identified two necessary conditions for adaptive efficiency: first, decentralised decision making and second, a feedback mechanism that eliminates errors more or less expeditiously. It is only in adaptively efficient economies where the tremendous potential of specialisation and trade can be realised, as these rely on ‘…contracts across time and space and with unknown second parties…’.38 These contracts cannot exist without a favourable institutional framework, including formal rules such as property rights and a judicial system that enforces contract rights; nor could these contracts exist without informal rules, such as a high degree of trust and respect for the formal rules. New Tools for the Constitutional Bench 45 31 DC North ‘Transaction Costs, Institutions, and Economic History’ (1984) 140 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 7 at 7-8. 32 DC North (note 23 above) at 3 33 W Kasper & M E Streit Institutional Economics: Social Order and Public Policy (1998) at 28. 34 DC North ‘Five Propositions about Institutional Change’ in J Knight & I Sened (ed) Explaining Social Institutions (1995) 15 at 15. 35 North (note 34 above); Easterly (note 11 above) passim. 36 Easterly (note 11 above) at 177. 37 North (note 30 above) at 109. 38 North (note 30 above) at 109. 4 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E Such an institutional approach accords an important role to the State. Kasper and Streit list a number of reasons why government enforcement of institutions are often desirable, including the state’s comparative advantage in power; government’s credibility; the potential ambiguity of internal rules; the ability of the state to implement rules dispassionately; free riding; the tragedy of the commons and finally, prisoner-dilemma type situations can often be resolved with credible external commitments. In the next section constitutional rights are regarded as important examples of such formal institutions. Mancur Olsen has shown how the distribution of favourable institutions internationally helps us to untangle some of the puzzling stylised facts of economic growth, for example that poor countries would not, unconditionally, be catching up with the rich countries, but that some poor countries – those with favourable institutions, creating adaptive efficiency – would enjoy catch-up growth. 39 This is not a circular argument, with Olsen, North and others equating ‘good institutions’ ex post to those institutions found in rich or fast growing countries. On the contrary, it is a posi- tive theory of social change that yields empirically testable hypotheses (using various measures of institutional quality).40 There is an extensive literature that applies institutional economics to economic history. Douglass North and Mancur Olson have been seminal in this field.41 Other important contributions have been made inter alia by Baumol, Eggertsson, Grilli, Masciandaro and Tabellini, de Long and Shleifer and Acemoglu.42 More recently, the empirical importance of institutions has been investigated using formal econometric tests. Some of these use simple graphical correlations between various measures of ‘good governance’ and different dimensions of economic performance.43 More sophisticated econometric techniques were used by inter alia Knack and Keefer, Hall and Jones, Clague, Keefer, Knack and Olson, Acemoglu, Johnson and Robinson and Rodrik, Subramanian and Trebbi to investigate the importance of empirical relevance of institutions in economic growth.44 In summary, the positive analysis of economic growth (in a vast literature that has received considerable attention from economists over the last twenty years) has yielded the ten- 39 ‘We know some institutional remedies that help matters, even if they are no panaceas. If only rule of law, democracy, independent central banks, independent finance ministers, and other good-quality institutions can be put in place, the endless cycle of bad policies and poor growth can come to an end’: Easterly (note 11 above) at 279. 40 A critical review of these attempts to quantify institutional quality is offered by J Aron ‘Growth and Institutions: A Review of Evidence’ (2000) 15(1) The World Bank Observer 99. 41 North (note 31 above) passim; North (note 30 above) passim; North (note 34 above) passim; Olsen ‘The Rise and Decline of Nations: Economic Growth, Stagflation, and Social Rigidities’ (1982) passim. 42 WJ Baumol. ‘Entrepreneurship: Productive, Unproductive and Destructive’ (1990) 89 Journal of Political Economy 893; T Eggertsson Economic Behaviour and Institutions (1990) passim; V Grilli, D Masciandaro et al ‘Institutions and Policies’ (1991) Economic Policy 341; JB de Long & A Shleifer ‘Princes and Merchants: European City Growth before the Industrial Revolution’ (1993) 36 Journal of Law and Economics 671; D Acemoglu ‘Root Causes. A Historical Approach to Assessing the Role of Institutions in Economic Development’ (2003) 40 Finance and Development 27. 43 A typical example is the strong positive correlation between the number of procedures required for regis- tering a new business and an index measuring corruption in the same economy. See World Bank World Development Report 2002. Building Institutions for Markets (2002) at 7. 44 S Knack & P Keefer ‘Institutions and Economic Performance: Cross Country Tests Using Alternative Institutional Measures’ (1995) 7 Economics and Politics 207; R Hall & CI Jones ‘Why do Some Countries Produce so Much More Output per Worker than Others’ (1999) 114 Quarterly Journal of Economics 83; Acemoglu (note 42 above); D Rodrik, A Subramanian et al ‘Institutions Rule: The Primacy of Institutions over Geography and Integration in Economic Development’ (2002) NBER Working Paper 9305. tative conclusion that institutions (as defined here) are amongst the most central determinants of long run growth and economic development. These institutions are also crucial for the sus- tained productivity growth which is the other major determinant of sustained technological growth. Taken together, the importance (even dominance) of institutions and technology growth undermine the sometimes intuitive view that economic development is mainly a matter of acquiring more resources.45 This result has an important implication for the progressive realisation of social and eco- nomic rights. It should shift the attention of government and the Constitutional Court from an exclusive concern with mobilising resources to a focus on the institutional matrix in society and the considerable role that government and the Constitutional Court play in the maintenance and evolution of that matrix. 46 The interest in this project lies beyond establishing the theoretical and empirical impor- tance of institutions, though. At stake is the difficult issue of institutional change and specif- ically how the Constitutional Court might participate in the institutional change associated with the realisation of social and economic rights in South Africa. The institutional literature referred to above includes theories of social change which incorporates positive and negative rights as institutions and which explains the observed international distribution of material prosperity. North derived two important implications of the theory of institutional change from this literature: firstly, that institutional change is likely to be incremental and secondly, that insti- tutional change is likely to be path dependent. 47 Both observations have interesting impli- cations for the possibility of theoretical drag in the realisation of social and economic rights. If institutional change is mostly gradual, as opposed to revolutionary, then we should adapt our expectations of the time horizon involved in the realisation of such change accordingly. This is not a defeatist attitude; rather it utilises the theoretical modelling of institutional change, and the historical record, to inform reasonable expectations. It is important for all the stakeholders in society, but especially for the Constitutional Court in this regard, to have reasonable expec- tations regarding the horizon over which institutional change occurs. The importance of reasonable expectations is closely associated with the likely path depend- ence of institutional change. The latter means that changes to the institutional matrix (that will affect the relative incentives for productive activity and rent seeking) have to be approached very carefully, as the possibility of ending in an underdevelopment trap is not simply theoreti- cal. Indeed, dozens of societies remain trapped in such circumstances today.48 It follows that the Constitutional Court should, as it wrestles with the interpretation and realisation of social and economic rights in South Africa, bear in mind the incremental character of institutional change and the path dependency which both raises the importance of moving forward in pres- ent circumstances and of avoiding injudicious moves down an ill-fated path where rent-seeking dominates productive choices. New Tools for the Constitutional Bench 47 45 Easterly (note 11 above) at 279. 46 The present literature on economic growth is, therefore, at odds with claims made in this regard by, for example, Chetty that ‘the pace and extent of development is ultimately determined by the resource con- straints’. See K Chetty ‘The Public Finance Implications of Recent Socio-Economic Rights Judgments’ (2002) 6 Law, Democracy and Development 231 at 234. 47 This emphasis on the slow moving and contextualised evolution of institutions reminds of Popper’s case for piecemeal social reform mentioned above (note 13). See also North (note 34 above) at 15. 48 Easterly (note 11 above) at 163. 4 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E V Rights as Institutions The New Institutional Economics provides an analytical framework for thinking about rights as an important subset of the institutional framework. Such a framework is useful to analyse both the role played by various rights in a given society and the role-players involved in secur- ing and exercising the rights. Thinking about rights as institutions provides a perspective in the rights literature that is complementary to perspectives gained from the philosophical and legal literature. Of particular interest for the purposes of this project is that the perspective gained from the New Institutional Economics offers one bridge between normative theories and legal analysis of social and political rights on the one hand and positive theories of social change (in which these rights play a central role) on the other. 49 First generation human rights are often called negative freedoms as they require the protec- tion of a private sphere of control.50 It is often advantageous for these rights to be defined and maintained by a state. The definition and maintenance of property rights is a typical – and for economists crucially important – example of an institution that lowers transaction costs as dis- cussed above. Second generation human rights, such as the right to health care, to education, to housing, employment and so on, are ‘positive rights’ in Berlin’s terminology.51 In contrast with the pri- vate sphere of control created by the first generation rights, the second-generation rights are aimed at empowering people to participate in society by providing access to resources and by defining a certain minimum standard of living.52 These rights, and the manner of their realisa- tion, also affect the incentives in society considerably. However their impact on incentives is not necessarily in the same manner as that of the first generation rights, nor necessarily even in the same direction. Economists have studied the respective roles of positive and negative rights in the institu- tional matrix. Specifically, economists are concerned with the potential behavioural implica- tions of different ways in which the realisation of rights could obtain. For example, economists are concerned with the intended but also with the unintended consequences of any intervention such as the definition of a minimum core for the concept of socio-economic rights by the Constitutional Court. To this end economists use their rational choice theory to trace the intended and unintended consequence of such institutional innovations.53 In the modern economics literature such concerns have been formalised in the Lucas-critique, according to which policy authorities should realise that behaviour in society will not be invari- ant to policy interventions.54 Behaviour and policies interact in this dynamic manner since poli- cies change the incentives of private and public decision makers. The same is true of social and 49 The New Institutional Economics analytical framework also provides alternative theories of the emergence of rights, but that falls beyond the scope of this project. I Sened ‘The Emergence of Individual Rights’ in J Knight & I Sened (ed) Explaining Social Institutions (1995) 161, offers an interesting recent example. 50 For A Sen ‘The Possibility of Social Choice’ (1999) 89 American Economic Review 349 at 363, these neg- ative liberties (or rights) constitute the ‘process aspect’ of liberty, that is the ‘choices over private domains, no matter what we may or may not achieve’. 51 I Berlin ‘Two Concepts of Liberty’ in I Berlin Fours Essays on Liberty (1969) 118. 52 For Sen (note 50 above) at 363 these positive rights define the ‘opportunity aspect’ of liberty, that is they ‘…can help us to achieve what we would choose to achieve in our respective private domains.’ 53 Posner (note 8 above) at 3. 54 RJ Lucas ‘Econometric Policy Evaluation: A Critique’ in K Brunner & AH Meltzer (ed) The Phillips Curve and Labour Markets (1976) 19 at 25. economic (and indeed, civil and political) rights, as has been demonstrated by the New Institutional Literature referred to above. The implication of the Lucas-critique for constitutional courts is similar to the implication for other policy authorities, that is: the Constitutional Court requires a fully articulated behav- ioural model (as opposed to broad stylised facts and general behavioural observations) before it can responsibly anticipate the outcomes of its decisions with respect to, inter alia, changes in the implementation of social and economic rights. In other words, the Constitutional Court requires a positive theory of behaviour in society, calibrated with the behavioural parameters of the actual society, in addition to the normative parameters of the society towards which the Court or anybody else may be striving. And the Court should not impose normative or ideo- logical priors on the role of various rights in such a positive theory of behaviour and social change. Though legal scholars have also been enthusiastic to attribute an important role to rights in their theory of social change, their analysis has often been strikingly different form that sketched in the preceding paragraphs. Scholars such as de Vos and Klare have drawn strong conclusions about the role of social and economic rights in support of the transformative char- acter of the South African Constitution and the apparent impediment of negative rights in that regard.55 Many of these accounts share the assumption that South Africa’s particular history required transformative social and economic rights to prevent a Bill of (first generation) Rights from preserving the unjust economic and social status quo. Pierre de Vos identified a negative component of a right that ‘…places a duty on the state to respect the specific right by not interfering with its enjoyment…[which] is the non-transforma- tive aspect of the right, as it attempts to preserve the existing situation in a society without ref- erence to the larger social and economic context or the transformative goals of the Constitution’; and again ‘there will, of course, often be a tension between the negative and pos- itive aspects of the various rights because the negative aspect of the right is primarily aimed at freezing the status quo while the positive aspect is aimed at achieving a society that would look dramatically different from the one we live in now’.56 Hanri Mostert refers to the ‘inherent contradictions’ of ‘assuming that the constitutional pro- tection and regulation of private property in South Africa is a tool for both protecting individ- ual freedom and security and initiating social change’.57 In the fourth Bram Fischer memorial lecture Justice Moseneke was also emphatic in carving a role for the Constitutional Court as an agent of transformation: ‘… the Constitution enjoins the judiciary to uphold and advance its transformative design’ and ‘…transformative adjudica- New Tools for the Constitutional Bench 49 55 P de Vos ‘Grootboom, the Right of Access to Housing and Substantive Equality as Contextual Fairness’ (2001) 17 SAJHR 258 at 260; K Klare ‘Legal Culture and Transformative Constitutionalism’ (1998) 14 SAJHR 146 at 169. Sunstein (note 5 above) at 4 distinguishes between broadly ‘preservative’ and broadly ‘transformative’ constitutions and classifies South Africa’s Final Constitution as ‘… the world’s leading example of a transformative constitution’. It is possible to read a tension between Sunstein’s favourable analysis of the transformative character of the South African Constitution and his concerns a decade earli- er in CA Sunstein ‘On Property and Constitutionalism’ (1991) Chicago Law and Economics Working Paper no 3 at 14, where he expressed serious reservations about the inclusion of ‘aspirations’ in a constitution. For a number of other perspectives on the concept of a transformative constitution and the associated role of rights see the volume edited by H Botha, AJ van der Walt & J van der Walt (note 3 above). 56 De Vos (note 55 above) at 273-274. 57 H Mostert ‘Liberty, Social Responsibility and Fairness in the Context of Constitutional Property Protection and Regulation’ in H Botha, AJ van der Walt & J van der Walt (eds) (note 3 above) 131 at 131. 5 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E tion must be put to the task of achieving (in conjunction with the other organs of the state and diverse organs of civil society) social redistributive justice. The primary purpose of the Constitution is to intervene in unjust, uneven and impermissible power and resource distribu- tions, in order to restore substantive equality, permissive or tolerable in a country, which has committed to foundational values such as are found in our Constitution’.58 Dennis Davis argued that if negative rights that protect a private sphere of control were priv- ileged by the Constitution and the Constitutional Court then ‘…much of the apartheid legacy would continue to be immune from the imperative of changing the essentials of apartheid soci- ety…’.59 On this issue the economic and legal literatures are evidently at odds. The description of rights as institutions above did not mention preserving the status quo. On the contrary, the dis- cussion emphasised that first generation rights, inter alia, are an integral part of a theory of social change. The gap between the two approaches is especially wide with respect to a claim, such as that of de Vos, that there is an ‘obvious’ tension between negative and positive aspects of rights in their transformative impact.60 Klaaren gives a concrete character to this tension by referring to a spectrum along which one might place the different understandings of the transformative potential of a constitution, start- ing with a minimal interpretation of a classically liberal type at one end and ending with a ‘rad- ically democratic’ interpretation at the other.61 The positive study of actual change in society (as described above) does not lend itself to such a one dimensional ranking. It might be true that the associated social change in what Klaaren characterises as a classically liberal under- standing of the Constitution is decentralised, but that does not detract from (i) the dynamic character of decentralised societies, or (ii) the magnitude of the change that has occurred in these societies over the past two centuries, nor (iii) from the widespread distribution of benefits in developed societies.62 The dynamic contribution of, for example, property rights to social change is associated with the incentives it creates as an institution:63 firstly, it creates incentives for the efficient alloca- 58 Moseneke (note 4 above) at 314, 318. 59 D Davis ’Elegy to Transformative Constitutionalism’ in H Botha, AJ van der Walt & J van der Walt (eds) (note 3 above) 57 at 58. 60 De Vos (note 55 above) at 274. M Pieterse ‘Beyond the Welfare State: Globalisation of Neo-liberal Culture and the Constitutional Protection of Social and Economic Rights in South Africa’ (2003) 14 Stellenbosch LR 3 at 18 chooses to articulate this tension in an analytical scheme whereby civil and political rights are associated with a ‘neo-liberal’ ideology of the state’s role in a market economy. In his ideological discourse Pieterse argues that neo-liberalist conceptions of society are ‘…contrary to the goals of social transforma- tion in that it requires that current distribution patterns are to be left intact…’. 61 J Klaaren ‘An Institutional Interpretation of Socio-Economic Rights and Judicial Remedies after TAC’ in H Botha, AJ van der Walt & J van der Walt (eds) (note 3 above) 105 at 107. 62 RJ Lucas ‘Some Macroeconomics for the 21st Century’ (2000) 14 Journal of Economic Perspectives 159 at 166. 63 This dynamic interpretation of, for example, property rights is not restricted to the economics literature. Legal scholars such as Cass Sunstein have acknowledged the same, for example: CR Sunstein ‘On Property and Constitutionalism’ (1991) Chicago Law and Economics Working Paper no 3 at 11. But Sunstein (note 63 above) at 11 goes further to argue that property rights are not just crucial to economic development and change, but added the political philosophy proposition that ‘…one of the best ways to destroy a democrat- ic system is to ensure that the distribution of wealth and resources is unstable and constantly up for new evaluation by the political process…a constitutional system that respects private property should be regard- ed, not as an effort to oppose liberal rights to collective self-government, but instead as a way to fortify dem- ocratic processes’. While that argument is not pursued in this chapter, it is consistent with and reinforces the ideas stated here. Further, he added immediately that a system of property rights requires the support of a tion of productive resources by allowing the property owner to appropriate the gains of em- ploying different factors of production. Secondly, property rights facilitate the complex co-ordi- nation of decentralised decisions that characterise a market economy and that avoids the rela- tively clumsy coordination of a centralised system. Thirdly, property rights offer one (often particularly efficient) solution to the problem of externalities. Mainstream economics predict many adverse consequences from the imprecise de jure and de facto allocation of property rights, including the tragedy of the commons and under-provision due to externalities.64 Finally, as explored in the previous section, property rights lower transaction costs and contribute to the stability and predictability of behaviour which is crucial for the dynamic efficiency brought by specialisation and trade in a decen- tralised system. Absent such rights, transactions are often prohibitively expensive due to the arbitrary behaviour of contracted parties and the unenforceability of agreements. In such a state of affairs the incentives for investing in physical and human capital as well as technolo- gy – three components crucial to economic development – are seriously compromised. In contrast with many legal scholars, economists argue (using a theory consistent with the historical record and econometric investigation) that the private sector is often the most dynam- ic force in society, while the public sector has often prevented the transformation of society. 65 Or, as William Easterly expressed the same argument more forcefully: ‘Because becoming rich – that is, growth – is so sensitive to the incentive to lower present consumption in return for higher future income, anything that mucks up that incentive will affect growth. The suspect for mucking up incentives is government’.66 Economic development, or the transformation to greater and shared prosperity, is not something that is done to a country (not by any branch of government); it is generally a decentralised and highly complex process which society effects on herself, given (at a minimum) a favourable institutional setting. Hayek has long since argued that a desire for change does not, as such, prejudge the choice of social and political model.67 A desire for the change associated with economic development does not prejudge whether that change should be centralised or decentralised. The desire for transformation in South Africa does not, therefore, prejudge whether such change should be centralised or decentralised; whether the Constitution should provide the framework against which the transformation of this society is to unfold, or whether it should be a tool with which the Constitutional Court will transform society. Such issues cannot be settled a priori, or on normative grounds, as Edmund Burke observed about the revolution in France: ‘The science of constructing a commonwealth, or renovating it, or reforming it, is, like every other experimental science, not to be taught a priori…[since] very New Tools for the Constitutional Bench 51 system of social and economic rights to create not ‘economic equality – a truly disastrous goal – but instead to bring about genuine equality of opportunity and, freedom, for all people in society, from desperate con- ditions’: Sunstein (note 63 above) at 12. 64 RH Coase ‘The Institutional Structure of Production’ in RH Coase (ed) Essays on Economics and Economists (1994) 3 at 10. 65 North (note 23 above) passim. In contrast, Pieterse (note 60 above) at 15 claims that the ‘evidence is over- whelming that [economic growth does]… not translate into better conditions for citizens’. The latter is admittedly an extreme version of the view that there is a tension between growth-supporting civil and polit- ical rights and socio-economic rights. It is also an empirical view that is unsupported by the data. See D Dollar & A Kraay ‘Growth is Good for the Poor’ (2001) World Bank Policy Research Working Paper Series 2587; X Sala-i-Martin ‘The World Distribution of Income’ (2002) NBER Working Paper 8933. 66 Easterly (note 11 above) at 235. 67 FA Hayek The Constitution of Liberty (1960) at 399. 5 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E plausible schemes, with very pleasing commencements, have often shameful and lamentable conclusions’.68 A positive theory of social change is required to judge which of these two models are more likely to support social transformation in South Africa. Absent such a theory, the Constitutional Court cannot judge how it might contribute to social transformation, except if the justices held the Utopian doctrine that amassing enough (political and economic) power is sufficient to see their project carried through. Moseneke escaped from this Utopianism danger by the mecha- nism of accountability. Constitutional Court Justices should, Moseneke argued, understand that they ‘are responsible for the social and distributive consequences that result from these choices, and should be judged accordingly’.69 But in this way Moseneke moved a long way towards a positive theory where monitoring of actual outcomes and (possibly) decentralised evaluation occurs. This small step by Moseneke seems most promising for this project about theories of social justice. Despite the discordance mentioned in this section, the success of the collaborative effort between economists and jurists in the field of law and economics, which has improved both our understanding of society and our understanding of the implications of the legal system, demon- strates that the positive theory of economics and legal theory might often be complementary.70 The ‘social and distributive consequences’ at stake in this consideration of social and econom- ic rights are, in addition to all their normative connotations, fundamentally empirical. This sug- gests a field where economists and jurists might cooperate to sharpen the theoretical hypothe- sis and the relevant empirical tests. 71 A positive theory of social change will also be required if the Constitutional Court is to adju- dicate the many issues that follow from having included social and economic rights in the Constitution. Here is a short list of contemporary examples: 1. The long term affordability as well as the incentive effects of the proposed basic income grant.72 2. The implications for monetary policy, wage negotiations, inflation expectations and so on, if social assistance was index-linked.73 3. The impact on the future supply and cost of medical services if the ‘certificate of need’ (Chapter 6 of the National Health Bill) for health care professionals impinges on the right of individuals to choose the location of their practise. 4. The impact of an expanded social assistance network on economic growth. Liebenberg refers to ‘…strong arguments… that social assistance programmes complement and support economic growth’ but offers no evidence to support these arguments.74 68 E Burke ‘Reflections on the Revolution in France’ in E Burke (ed) On Taste; On the Sublime and Beautiful; Reflections on the French Revolution; A Letter to a Noble Lord (1937) 143 at 198-199. 69 Moseneke (note 4 above) at 317. 70 RH Coase ‘Economics and Contiguous Disciplines’ in RH Coase (ed) (note 64 above) 34 at 37. 71 Justice Posner cautioned that ‘…the taste for fact that I would like to see developed in judges and law pro- fessors will turn to gall if unaccompanied by a taste for theory – not normative theory, so not what passes for theory in constitutional law, but positive theory, economic or otherwise, that guides the search for sig- nificant facts’. See RA Posner Overcoming Law (1995) at 427. 72 S Liebenberg ‘The Right to Social Assistence: The Implications of Grootboom for Policy Reform in South Africa’ (2001)17 SAJHR 231 at 254. 73 Liebenberg (note 72 above) at 241. 74 Liebenberg (note 72 above) at 256. Economics can provide the positive theory needed to complement legal theory in these cases, as has occurred in the USA in recent decades.75 Gauri provides a recent example of how positive economic theory could be used explicitly in the service of justiciable social and economic rights.76 She disputes the sometimes sharp delineation between an ‘economic approach’ to social and economic rights that focuses on incentives and the role of markets and prices on the on hand and a ‘rights based approach’ focusing on Constitutional Law on the other. In specif- ic examples – Gauri considers health care and education provision in Brazil – the two approach- es often require complementary interventions.77 There is no disagreement between the positive and normative approaches on the importance of, for example, improved health care provision for all citizens, especially the poor. Whereas the normative theories might emphasise the role of basic health care in almost any conception of a decent and responsible life or appeal to the wide ranging ‘equality clause’ in the South African Constitution, positive theories emphasise the importance of such health care as an enabling step that allows a person to participate socially and productively. In practice the two approaches would often meet, as in the TAC case where both normative and positive evaluation of the existing government programme concurred. 78 Notwithstanding this scope for agreement, a constitutional court which hopes to encourage transformation through justiciable social and economic rights will have to incorporate positive theory when undertaking judicial review of positive programmes. The relevant positive theory in such a case goes beyond the cost-benefit analysis often associated with economics79 to con- sider the institutional nature of principal-agent problems80 associated with many policies.81 Indeed, Barberton contrasts two interpretations of ‘progressive realisation of social and eco- nomic rights, from the perspective of economics, with the first focused on inputs and the sec- ond on outputs.82 This distinction becomes non-trivial when considering the principal-agent problem inherent to a focus on outcomes. From the principal-agent or ‘outcomes’ perspective New Tools for the Constitutional Bench 53 75 Posner (note 8 above) at 2. 76 V Gauri ‘Social Rights and Economics. Claims to Health Care and Education in Developing Countries’ (2003) World Bank Policy Research Paper 3006 at 3. 77 Gauri (note 76 above) at 11. 78 Minister of Health and Others v Treatment Action Campaign and Others (No 2) 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC) at 116, 122, 130, 131. 79 This perspective also moves beyond considering the social and economic context of the problem. While the context is often an important part of the analysis, the institutional concern is explicitly dynamic and with a dynamic analysis the present context can only ever be a starting point. 80 A principal-agent problem arises when one party (called the principal) is interested in certain ‘good’ behav- iour by another party (called the agent) but the principal either has insufficient information or insufficient means to ensure the desired behaviour by the agent. These problems typically occur when the agent’s goal is unclear, unobservable or otherwise hard or expensive to monitor, or where the principal and agent have different goals. In these circumstances, the incentive effect of the contract between the principal and agent can have a material effect on the behaviour of the agent and hence the efficiency of the outcome from the principal’s perspective. See JE Stiglitz ‘Principal and Agent’ in J Eatwell, M Milgate & P Newman (eds) The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics (1987) 966 at 967. 81 Principal-agent problems are central to the attempts at progressively realising many social and economic rights. Education is a case in point in South Africa where a massive expansion in resources devoted to pri- mary and secondary education has yet failed to deliver an improvement in the quality of education offered. See S van der Berg & R Burger ‘Social Delivery in South Africa’ (2003) Stellenbosch Report prepared for the CDE. By implication, judicial review of programmes related to these rights have to grapple with the insti- tutional features of the policy that shape the incentives for public and private behaviour. 82 C Barberton ‘“Progressive Realisation” of Socio-Economic Rights’ (1999) 2 Economic and Social Rights Review 1 at 2. 5 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E the judicial review of programmes for the progressive realisation of social and economic rights has to consider issues such as transparency, accountability, monitoring and other features that affect the incentives of public and private behaviour under such programmes. Solving a principal-agent problem requires explicit attention to the flow of information (and hence focus on transparency and participation) to monitoring (with a consequent focus on accountability and empowerment) and to the incentives created by any policy or judicial review of that policy. It is the analysis of incentive effects which often distinguishes the positive ap- proach from the normative approach when the emphasis shifts to moral hazard and adverse selection considerations. Principal-agent problems require a careful design of incentives to align the expected behav- iour of the agent (the government in many social rights cases) with the goals of the principal (the presently disadvantaged in a typical rights case). In positive economic theory it is institu- tions which shape these incentives and it was argued above that rights can often be understood as a subset of these institutions. However, there is no unique combination of institutions which is invariably optimal for all societies or for the same society at different times. On the contrary, the optimality of institutions – and hence of optimal role of social and economic rights – requires a positive analysis of the existing matrix of formal and informal institutions, to ensure that changes (motivated by an appeal to rights) do not create perverse incentives. Such an analy- sis of incentives, information flow, transparency and accountability, is an application of a pos- itive theory of social change, and the arguments of such a theory are what I have called the ‘new tools for the Constitutional Bench’ in this chapter. New tools from the positive social science should, on the argument in this chapter, be added to the tests of reasonableness which the Constitutional court has used in its judicial review of social-economic rights cases to date, notably the Soobramooney,83 Grootboom84 and TAC85 cases. The Constitutional Court spelled out this reasonableness test at some length in Groot- boom, arguing that: …A reasonable programme therefore must clearly allocate responsibilities and tasks to the different spheres of government and ensure that the appropriate financial and human resources are available…Mere legislation is not enough. The State is obliged to act to achieve the intended result, and the legislative measures will invariably have to be supported by appropriate, well directed policies and programmes by the exec- utive. These policies must be reasonable both in their conception and their imple- mentation…balanced and flexible and make provision for attention to housing crises and to short, medium and long term needs…those whose needs are the most urgent and whose ability to enjoy all rights therefore is most in peril, must not be ignored by the measures aimed at achieving realisation of the right…86 It is not possible for the Constitutional Court to carry out the judicial review envisaged by its own test of reasonableness without engaging in positive social science.87 Absent positive 83 Soobramoney v Minister of Health, Kwazulu-Natal 1998 (1) 765 (CC). 84 Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC). 85 Minister of Health and Others v Treatment Action Campaign and Others (No 2) 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC). 86 Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC) at para 39-44. 87 D Brand ’The Proceduralisation of South African Socio-Economic Rights Jurisprudence, or ‘What are Socio- Economic Rights For?’ in H Botha, AJ van der Walt & J van der Walt (eds) (note 3 above) fn 45 has sug- social science the Court will not be in a position to weigh intended and unintended conse- quences – and the issues here are not those of cost-benefit analysis alone, but especially princi- pal-agent problems. Further the Court would not know whether a proposed programme falls within the set of reasonably conceived programmes without method and knowledge to judge the empirical literature that evaluates such policies. Nor is this an attempt to push the Court into a new field or endeavour. On the contrary, the Court is already practicing social science when it implements its own reasonableness test. VI Conclusion In this chapter I argued that accepting the inclusion of socio-economic rights in a Constitution such as South Africa’s with a transformative vision does not prejudge whether such transfor- mation should be centralised or decentralised; socio-economic rights are compatible with both. Understanding the actual transformation of societies, however, requires a positive theory of social change and it was suggested above that economics could offer a successful positive the- ory of decentralised change that can analyse the role of rights as institutions in social change. This theory – drawn from the New Institutional Economics – does not model the same tension between first and second generation rights in the process of social change as is often presumed a priori in the legal literature. For this reason alone the theory would be useful to consider. But there are two further reasons for including the New Institutional Economics in the new tools of the Constitutional Bench, that is: it offers a logically and empirically successful positive the- ory of social change and it informs the social science implicit in the Court’s own test of rea- sonableness. New Tools for the Constitutional Bench 55 gested as much when he suggested that within a model of judicial review the standard of scrutiny in the ‘means -ends’ reasonableness model evidently adopted by the Constitutional Court operates on two levels: first, an indication of how the Court will decide whether a programme is appropriately related to the stat- ed goal and second, the burden of proof or evidence or persuasion that the Court will require of the parties in such a matter. A positive theory of social science is well suited to addressing these questions. Social Justice and Theological Method FA N I E D U T O I T Programme Manager, Institute for Justice and Reconciliation, Cape Town; Associated Researcher, Faculty of Theology, Stellenbosch University The Spirit of the Lord has been given to me. For he has anointed me. He has sent me to bring good news to the poor, To proclaim liberty to the captives And to the blind new sight, To set the downtrodden free To proclaim the Lord’s year of favour.1 I Introduction A range of religions envision utopian societies as their ultimate goal. In the Torah, a time is pre- dicted when a ‘river of justice’ will flood the land. Everyone will be given enough to eat. Each person will receive a home. The weakest and poorest will have their dignity restored. Fighting will cease, swords beaten into ploughshares and spears turned into pruning hooks. Even lambs and wolves will lie down in peace. This vision is reintroduced in Christ’s words quoted above some 1000 years later, where the liberation of the poor and marginalised is singled out as a key indicator of justice, and a first step towards peace associated with the ‘Lord’s year of favour’. There are differing opinions about whether such theological idealism motivates quietism or activism. Perhaps it relates to both. On the one hand, the difference between reality and such a grand vision may seem too great, motivating a retreat into the fatalist acceptance of the pow- ers to be – in the hope that God, one day, will intervene. Utopian visions can become the opium of the masses. Seeing no real hope, people find religious solace in beautiful dreams. On the other hand, for ‘court theologians’ whose interests are represented by those in the pound seats, the temptation to become defenders of the status quo often results in compro- mised, muted social critique. Since the Constantinian era first saw Christianity become the offi- cial faith of the Roman Empire, every regime has had ‘court theologians’ who, in God’s name, specialise in justifying the unjustifiable. But there have always also been the extremists, who seek change that destroys more than it 1 Lk 4:18-19. builds. The Crusaders left a trail of destruction in the name of social justice. Believing that theirs is the only truth, fundamentalist believers in this mould have, over the ages, resorted to un- precedented violence in the name of justice – and often achieved the opposite. This essay explores some of the conditions under which theological discourse facilitate pos- itive activism. We are interested in a particular type of change – towards a fairer, more inclu- sive society, in fairer, more inclusive ways. The process is vital. We see inclusivity, as it takes shape in the logic and discourses of reconciliation, as a precondition, an enabler, of justice. Justice is forged from consensus and through cooperation. It is by working together that adver- saries create the conditions for growth and prosperity. Without revisiting the protracted debate about the relation between theory and praxis, the assumption is that political praxis and academic theory do, in fact, exert influence on one another. We assume that theoretical reflection influences policies and practises, whether as source of, or as reflection on, praxis. Provided it finds it own voice, therefore, theoretical theology (but not abstract theology!) has a distinctive contribution to make to the quest for multifarious dimensions of justice. To concretise the discussion, I choose to focus specifically on Christian theology within the South African context. South African Christianity has produced liberating theologies, and, as we know only too well, deeply oppressive ones. This history emphasises the importance of ask- ing about the ‘ground rules’ for theological contributions towards social justice – in order to ensure both positive impact on society, as well as truthful witness to its own nature. It remains perplexing that progress towards social and economic justice is not more rapid. In the first section, I analyse this malaise by distinguishing between material and political imped- iments to justice. Political rights are, generally, better institutionalised than economic or social rights. Yet, it is often the lack of political will that impedes the progress of social and econom- ic justice. At the heart of this failure to act, I claim, lies a moral impasse that is central to the theological task.2 Social Justice and Theological Method 57 2 This lack of will to create a better world is highlighted in a crucial report, Human Security Now, presented to the United Nations Secretary-General, Kofi Annan on 1 May 2003 by the Co-Chairs of the Commission on Human Security, Sadako Ogata and Amartya Sen. The Sunday Independent, at the time, called it ‘prob- ably the most important document yet drawn up by an influential group of global citizens concerning the future of humanity’. The findings of the Commission concerning Africa were based on wide-ranging inter- views with citizens in 14 African countries, representing 26% of African nations. The commissioners sought to answer the question: ‘What makes people secure or insecure and what interventions are needed to address people’s concerns in this regard?’ Top of the list, not surprisingly, came poverty and lack of basic services, followed by violent conflict, refugees, poor governance, political instability and human rights abuses. Interestingly however, participants identified leadership, spirituality and morality, dignity and inter-group relations as the key to an African understanding of human security. The extent to which this seminal report identified the way forward in terms of relational matters, rather than material challenges, is telling of the measure to which material and human challenges combine to form the agenda for human development in Africa today. This is an important insight, not only for political analysts, but also for religious scholars and leaders seeking to define the role of faith in the development of Africa. It seems to open an opportunity for faith-based communities in the public arena and removes doubt that subjective aspects of human develop- ment have a role to play in Africa’s renewal process. The Commission on Human Security was established in January 2001 through the initiative of the Government of Japan and in response to the UN Secretary- General’s call at the 2000 Millennium Summit for a world ‘free of want’ and ‘free of fear.’ The Commission consisted of twelve prominent international figures. The full report is available at http://www.humansecuri- ty-chs.org/finalreport/index.html. 5 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E II South Africa and the Growing International Consensus on What Needs to be Done Part of the build-up towards a ‘Scenario 2015’ planning exercise of the United Nations in March 2005, was to identify ‘signs of hope’ for those concerned with the promotion of justice. One prominent such sign was the growing international consensus on developmental priorities for the next ten years. These priorities, known as the United Nations Millennium Development Goals (MDG), represent significant international consensus on global priorities on the road to a more just world. Ratified by heads of State and Governments and adopted by the UN General Assembly in New York on September 8, 2000, the Millennium Declaration states that signatories are ‘deter- mined to establish a just and lasting peace all over the world’. 3 To achieve this, six fundamen- tal values are identified, namely: freedom, equality, solidarity, tolerance, respect for nature and shared responsibility. The further formulation of eight specific Millennium Development Goals, along with an action plan, represents a significant achievement. Never before has there been such wide consensus about how to eradicate poverty.4 South Africa’s development project has taken root in and continues to be shaped by this new international idealism. How do South Africa’s achievements to date compare to the MDG? The feat of uniting warring adversaries in a single body politic that enjoys the support of the majority of South Africans, and that is based on a progressive Constitution, the writing of which was itself an exercise in democratic participation, remains the envy of many. That the transition was further cloaked in the discourses of reconciliation, accountability (albeit limited with amnesty provisions) and justice – representing an impressive framework for post-conflict recon- struction – moved even the most cynical observers to admiration. Add to this the operationali- sation of some of the world’s most expanded service delivery programmes such as housing, pri- mary health care and educational restructuring. On top of this, fiscal discipline and frugal gov- ernment spending have created the conditions for economic growth now perched at somewhere upward of 4% in a climate inspiring growing investor confidence. Is the miracle continuing? Many would seem to think so, and there seems to be plenty of reasons why they may be right. Yet, on the flipside, unlikely names such as Diepsloot and Phomolong have become symbols of growing discontent about the pace of service delivery that, ten years into democracy, is yet to touch the lives of many deeply poor communities. Perceptions, rightly or wrongly, that they 3 http://www.un.org/millennium/declaration/ares552e.htm. 4 To this end, the UN resolved, by 2015, to: 1 Halve the proportion of world’s people whose income is less than one dollar a day, and the proportion of the people who suffer from hunger. 2 Ensure that, by the same date, children everywhere, boys and girls alike, will be able to complete a full course of primary schooling 3 Ensure that girls and boys will have equal access to all levels of education. 4 Have reduced, by the same date, maternal mortality by three quarters, of their current rates. 5 Have reduced, by the same date, under-five child mortality by two-thirds, of their current rates. 6 Have, by then, halted, and begun to reverse, the spread of HIV/Aids, the scourge of malaria and other major diseases that afflict humanity, to provide special assistance to children orphaned by HIV/Aids. 7 Have achieved, by 2020, a significant improvement in the lives of at least 100 million slum dwellers as proposed in the ‘Cities Without Slums’ initiative and by the same date, to halve the proportion of the peo- ple are unable to reach or to afford safe drinking water. 8 Develop an open trading and financial system that is rules-based, predictable and non-discriminatory. This includes a commitment to good governance and addressing the special needs of the least developed countries. For more information, see http://www.un.org/millenniumgoals/. represent the ‘forgotten people’ are reinforced by the apparent infrastructural muscles, power lines, telecommunication grids and roads, bulging around them, but failing to make any direct impact on their lives. The sudden and fabulous wealth of the black elite, coupled with the South African government’s direct involvement in many parts of Africa, creates the impression of a jet-set elite that has relegated the original goals of the RDP, and even more treacherously, the liberation movement, to the back seat. Compounding this scenario of deepening poverty are the twin social scourges of HIV/AIDS and violent anti-social behaviour, including organised and domestic crime. The implosion of South Africa’s neighbour and main regional trading partner, Zimbabwe, to levels of political anarchy and economic meltdown reminiscent of apartheid South Africa, has not helped either. How does one make analytical sense of this complex situation? The Institute for Justice and Reconciliation, recognizing in its mission statement that reconciliation and justice are inter-relat- ed goals, produced a first-of-its-kind report in 2004 to investigate some of these issues. Entitled Taking Power in the Economy – Gains and Directions, this publication forms the first in an annu- al series of Economic Transformation Audits (TA) to hold up the mirror to the nation as a whole and ask: How are we doing in our quest towards a more socially and economically just society? This study was born in an attempt to move beyond simplistic assessments, either uncritical- ly positive, or one-sidedly negative. Four areas are assessed critically in terms of progress since 1994. These are unemployment, poverty, inequality and education. 5 As may be expected, the findings present a mixed scorecard. In terms of unemployment, the TA shows that despite the fact that a million new jobs had been created since 1994, the num- ber of jobseekers have also exploded, mainly as a result of rising rural deprivation and a steep incline in women work seekers. There is an increasing demand for skilled workers, but low- skills job have declined. These conditions have contributed to more poor people in 2001 in South Africa than in 1996. With some spectacular advances amongst those who have benefited from empowerment and fresh business opportunities, this reality has resulted in increasing inequality since 1996. Despite Black Economic Empowerment, the average African income as a percentage of white income fell to 6.99%. These negative findings need, however, to be balanced with massive increases in access to services to the poor. The TA shows that economic growth has been slow but steady, while inflation steadied downward. The TA claims further that the current BEE (Black economic empowerment) strat- egy is not yet an anti-poverty strategy. It is (still) largely a redistributive strategy. The current policy is therefore appropriately shifting towards a more broad-based approach, with empha- sis on skills-development, preferential procurement, employment equity and job-creation. Dubbed the ‘broken link’ by the TA, education has delivered relatively disappointing results towards producing a better-educated workforce with more mathematically skilled members. Schooling is not giving the youths the skills they need to embrace developmental opportunities. With more than 20% of the annual budget allocated to education, better output was envi- sioned. The problems seem to have to do with quality of teaching, availability of textbooks and school management.6 Social Justice and Theological Method 59 5 S Brown and A Fölscher Taking Power in the Economy – Gains and Directions (2004) at xi. 6 A 2005 Nelson Mandela Foundation/HSRC Report, Emerging Voices: A Report on Education in South African Rural Communities, asked 4332 respondents, including many teachers about the most important problems that teachers face. In first place, with 71% support, is lack of teaching aids, and second, at 60%, is lack of cooperation from parents. 6 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E So, is South Africa a more just society than ten years ago? Probably yes. Is there a sufficient concentration of minds on the eradication of poverty to ascertain that South Africa does not slide back into slow decay and anarchy? Probably not. We are not yet displaying the levels of societal consensus and efficiency required to deal with poverty within the timeframe allowed for by the UN referred to above or appropriate to the available political capital. The haunting question remains: given the high stakes, why is there not a broader and deeper sense of urgency to fight inequality, poverty, bad education and unemployment? This lack of urgency is not unique to South Africa; in fact, South Africa is probably more engaged with the fight to end poverty than most, and yet, even here, it seems unlikely that we will have achieved our goals by 2015. Early global assessments on progress towards the Millennium goals have also met with disap- pointment. It is no surprise therefore that implementation strategies are coming under scrutiny. 7 The debate is no longer about what needs to be done. It is now about when and through whom these goals are to be achieved– and how role players will be motivated to contribute. In South Africa, too, everyone seems to be in agreement that the poor should be helped. There is even agree- ment about who should do what and by when. The challenge remains to put into action these plans within an acceptable timeframe. The quest for justice, particularly equity, seems now more than ever, to be about political and moral stamina – and this where the debate becomes complex. III Two Possible Causes of the Malaise: Traumatised Societies and Growing Inequality A fundamental premise to help identify root causes of this malaise is the distinction between socio-economic (material) and more subjective dimensions (political will, human capacity) of justice. I contend that focusing on the former to the exclusion of the latter is a recipe for non- delivery. Socio-economic justice is not simply about the achievement of material challenges, infrastructural backlogs and trading links, vital as these are. Amartya Sen reminds us that devel- opment is about more than material reconstruction and development.8 It is about the restora- tion of human dignity and freedom, about fostering the capacity to choose lives that we value. Development, properly understood, is about more than creating economic opportunity. It is about creating the opportunities to become economically active. The multi-dimensional process of human development lies at the heart of the quest for jus- tice. In biblical terms there can be no justice without genuine peace, and peace starts with change in the hearts and minds of people. Development harbours profound political, social and psychological challenges for developing as well as developed countries. Yet, these dimensions are often overlooked. 7 On January 17th 2005 the most comprehensive action-plan yet to achieve the Millennium Goals was pub- lished. A blue-ribbon team of 265 of the world’s leading development experts drew up a package of scores of specific cost-effective measures that together could achieve the Millennium Goals. The prelude to this action plan states: ‘We have the opportunity in the coming decade to cut world poverty by half. Billions more people could enjoy the fruits of the global economy. Tens of millions of lives can be saved. The prac- tical solutions exist. The political framework is established. And for the first time, the cost is utterly afford- able. Whatever one’s motivation for attacking the crisis of extreme poverty—human rights, religious values, security, fiscal prudence, ideology—the solutions are the same. All that is needed is action. ‘The experts who contributed to this huge undertaking has shown without a doubt that we can still meet the Goals - if we start putting this plan into action right now’ said Prof JD Sachs, who leads the project. 8 A Sen Development as Freedom (1999). Thus, the failure to take into account the human factor in human development may be the cause for many retarded delivery processes. The importance of the human factor begs a num- ber of questions of all parties involved; the disempowered, the freshly empowered as well as the empowering: ● Developing countries struggle to find ways to empower people to embrace opportunities. Justice seems to require integrated restoration and healing processes where people explore ways to overcome bad memories, internalised forms of dehumanised identity and stereotyped divisions associated with intense suffering, oppression or violation. But these strategies seem thin on the ground. ● Developed countries, on the other hand, need to find ways to generate moral, political and economic solidarity that supersedes citizenship. There is an urgent need for a fairer and more accountable international trading and governance system where richer nations take steps to ensure greater power sharing and a more equitable international order. What is needed is a deeper sense of solidarity between the rich and the poor. Too much involvement by the rich in the affairs of the poor still bears the hallmark of patronising charity born of a lack of in- depth exposure, understanding and solidarity. Frightening and growing inequality may ex- plain deepening incomprehension and solidarity, despite a veritable explosion in news cov- erage and other global forms of information flows. These challenges exceed the normal ambit of political and economic activity. It requires ‘the extra mile’. Their unusual, ‘out-of-the-box’ character causes these challenges often to be ignored, but, left unattended, they have the potential to undermine the quest for justice. Justice includes the overcoming of the trauma associated with extreme poverty, oppression and violence at both personal and public levels. For anyone who doubts the intensity of per- sonal trauma caused by poverty, consider the following anecdote, recorded in an interview of the Institute for Justice and Reconciliation: My mother would come home to the six of us with one plate of food from the Madam. We would stand around her and hold out our hands. She would then divide the plate into six portions and place the pieces of food, bit by bit, into our open hands. Other nights, when there was nothing, she would keep up our spirits by boil- ing water with a brick or stone in the pot. Occasionally she would “test” the stone in the pot with a fork to inform us that the potatoes were not soft yet. At least we fell asleep with the hope that food would be on the table soon. This trauma is often exacerbated by political oppression and violence, gross inequality and social isolation all phenomena commonly associated with the poorest of the poor communities in developing countries. The subjective dimension to development goes beyond the psychological. Trauma works itself into the fibre of the social and political institutions of a society. Thus justice becomes a question of social transformation. It is not just about the healing of individuals. It is about social reconstruction and impacting the ethos of collectives. The systemic, structural dimensions of injustice remain embedded in the fibre of developing countries. To this end, turning decrepit and biased institutions into inclusive, transparent and democratic ones is one of the main chal- lenges of development efforts the world over. Institutionalised power-relations originating from an unjust past naturally resist such moves towards equity. Integration of former enemies at all Social Justice and Theological Method 61 6 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E levels of society becomes a central task. The question becomes: how does one facilitate condi- tions where former enemies may develop into business partners or opposition politicians with- in a democratic framework? A reconciliatory ethos envisions cycles of deepening engagement across divisions. A lack of this ‘reconciliatory ethos’ contributes, I contend, to unsustainable development. It explains the perplexing lack of enthusiasm, despite declarations to the opposite, of potential beneficiaries of development, as well as of potential drivers and donours. Justice requires solidarity and inclu- sive processes adhering to the logic of reconciliation, where the dignity of people is recognised and restored. We have a goal – we even have a plan. Yet we seem to lack the will to travel this road. The flesh is strong, but the spirit, seemingly, remains weak. Can theology help to motivate people towards the extra-ordinary efforts it will take to conquer human deprivation? IV Theological Possibilities In his Theology of Reconstruction, Charles Villa-Vicencio reminds us that responsible theology has to be utopian. Priests are obliged to be turbulent and annoyingly visionary in even the most socially responsible societies. And yet the church must also be realistically committed to what is attainable here and now as part of a greater vision.9 Utopian ideals, whatever the source, continue to have a role to play in the fight for justice. For one, they are able to rule out complacency and fatalism, and continue to spur social change. At the same time, utopian zeal can be dangerous. Emil Brunner writes that: ‘Christians cannot “sanctify” the world, that is, humanity, in such a manner as they sanctify themselves’.10 In what follows I unpack four traits, describing basic features of a theology for human devel- opment that may serve to help overcome some of the psychological, political and moral obsta- cles that lie at the root of the malaise of realising integrated justice for all. The four traits each have a thematic texture: each have a content that is derived from a par- ticular understanding of what is central to Christian theology. Each trait also has contextual rel- evance with the potential, so I contend, to have real impact on the social, political and moral landscapes we inhabit. The allocated space does not permit an extended application of these theological traits to the quest for justice. Moreover, the author is no development specialist. Yet, guidelines are pre- sented and preliminary observations made about how a theology shaped by particular concep- tions of grace, truth, hope and justice may serve the cause of socio-economic justice in the twen- ty-first century. Remarkably, it is now possible to envision the implementation of the UN’s MDG’s. In South Africa’s case at least, this task requires an enormous, concerted and unremitting effort. How can this be sustained? The temptation to rest on the laurels of South Africa’s considerable achievements grows only stronger with time. Stamina – political, moral and social – is required if the fight against poverty is be overcome. When operating, in the precarious space between fatalism and idealism, theology can foster responsible and creative contributions to the promo- tion of justice. 9 C Villa-Vicencio A Theology of Reconstruction – Nationbuilding and Human Rights (1992) at 31. 10 E Brunner Dogmatics (1950) at 315. (A) GRACE To be a voice for justice, theology needs to recognise itself as teleological. This is no convenient innovation. Theology is, in fact, teleological – always pulling towards a goal – always beyond itself. Theology is not content to refer to truth. It seeks to realise this truth. It does not rest until the goal is achieved. It longs and works for ideals it realises cannot be achieved immediately. Importantly, this dynamism does not depend on observers or admirers of theological truth. Theologians cannot sustain this restlessness. It is the object of theological enquiry itself that pulls, pushes and cajoles. Encountering the object of theology is transformative. But how is this restlessness to be understood? What is it that theology pushes towards? What/who is doing the pulling? Karl Barth, the Swiss theologian whose writings profoundly influ- enced 20th century theology, and who wrote in the time of deep social change in Europe between the first and second World Wars, claims that theology’s central focus is to be found in grace. Writing in 1918, as the hazy religio-cultural chauvinism that dominated Europe up to then began to dissolve, Barth seeks a uniquely Christian truth – something to distinguish itself from the folly of Euro- pean self-aggrandisation, and from forms of liberal theology absorbed into the culture of the time. Barth’s starting point is that humans have no capacity to enter into a relationship with God.11 Any link with the Divine has to be given to us from beyond ourselves. Once established, a relationship with the Divine cannot be ‘owned’. Theological truth never belongs to theolo- gians – it remains a free, unexpected gift whereever it occurs. Although grace falls beyond human capacity, it does not override or diminish humanity. In fact, it draws humans beyond themselves into communion with God and fellow human beings.12 God’s grace is the condition for human fulfilment, not the negation thereof. Human fulfilment, viewed theologically, lies beyond what is possible for human beings to attain or to become. Precisely because theology draws us towards this fulfilment, it remains restless. When theology relinquishes this restlessness, its distinctive contribution is lost. This happens when grace is no longer the focus. Theology becomes a ‘moralistic affair’, ‘indif- ferent to the question of man itself’, the question of human suffering and misery.13 Fully institu- tionalised, it becomes the voice of the well endowed and powerful. Therefore grace – as embodied in Jesus Christ – favours the poor and marginalised almost to the point of prejudice.14 The essence of the restlessness of true theology is found in its passion for the excluded, poor and marginalised. This also means that reconciliation – humanising engagement over divides – occupies a cen- tral place in Barth’s thought. God crosses, in freedom, the divide with the human race and establishes a new humanity. God shows solidarity with human beings in their hopelessness, cre- ating a new humanity through reconciliation. The restoration of justice coincides with the restoration of reconciled community, of restored fellowship. ‘Why Jesus’s existence was so unsettling on every side was that He set all programmes and principles in question’, writes Barth. To this end, ‘he enjoyed and displayed a remarkable free- dom…He simply revealed the limit and frontier of all these things – the freedom of the Kingdom of God. He existed in freedom and summoned others to it.’15 Social Justice and Theological Method 63 11 K Barth Church Dogmatics (1960) at 238. 12 G Hunsinger How to Read Karl Barth – The Shape of His Theology (1991) at 31f. 13 See DJ Smit ‘Paradigms of Radical Grace’ in C Villa-Vicencio (eds) On Reading Karl Barth in South Africa (1988) at 33. 14 Smit ‘Paradigms’ (note 13 above) at 23. 15 Smit ‘Paradigms’ (note 13 above) at 24. These quotations are from Barth (note 11 above) at IV/2. 6 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E Theology needs to be vigilant. When it is no longer determined by grace and becomes a self- reliant system of thought, it loses the dynamism that is the hallmark of divine grace. Public the- ology, aiming to promote socio-political justice, needs to orientate itself continuously towards this gift of grace. Above all, a theology steeped in grace realises its own needs and imperfec- tions, opening the door to deeper solidarity with those whose needs are perhaps emphasized by socio-economic deprivation and injustice. (B) TRUTH Yet grace can be cheap. When all is forgiven and accepted, when accountability dies in the cheap embrace of amnesia, the violation of human dignity becomes permanent. A justice built on forgetting injustice is not only unlikely to survive, it is fundamentally flawed. The restora- tion of human dignity, after periods of gross injustice, requires a search for truth and for acknowledgement, however hesitantly, however relative, however perspectival. A theology of human development has to compliment its focus on grace with a focus on truth. Truth represents more than a focus on neglected facts about degrees of poverty, suffering or violation. It is about creating the space for the oppressed to speak out for themselves, and for them to become conversation partners in the formation of the strategies to establish justice. The Truth and Reconciliation Commission understood its mandate to be the mediation of forgotten voices. To some extent (and with many shortcomings) it did succeed to bring these voices into the mainstream. Ten years later, there is again a need for South Africans to listen carefully. In our current political climate the voices of the poor and marginalised need amplification. But this requires mediation. These truths are not easily heard or understood. Communication between the disempowered and the rich and the poor cannot be taken for granted, for it has to cross the chasm of inequality that runs through the heart of the South African society, render- ing it one of the most unequal in the world. Theology may provide such mediation precisely because its truth-claims are inherently accommodating and inclusive. Theology’s ‘modest truth’ is a result of the nature of the way that God reveals Himself to the world, at once hiding as much as it reveals. God’s truth may be pres- ent in our world, but it is a subtle, ‘hidden’ presence, as Barth explains: The veil is thick. We do not possess the Word of God otherwise than in the mystery of its world-involvement. …Its form is not a suitable but an unsuitable medium for God’s presentation of Himself. It does not unveil, but rather veils it.16 The moment theological truth is captured, it dies. God’s truth breaks into human discourse, in a miraculous way, that is, through none of our doing, despite the fact that language ‘seen from our side’ has no capacity to produce the kind of truth-claims that would encapsulate the Divine, says Barth. God’s revelation remains God’s mystery.17 Thomas F Torrance writes about this concept of truth: Behind all this questioning on Barth’s part lies a deep humility before the face of Truth: in his recognition that the Truth will not and cannot be mastered by our dis- 16 Barth (note 11 above) at 188. 17 SF du Toit Ideas of Truth and Revelation in the Light of the Challenge of Postmodernism (University of Oxford: DPhil Thesis, 1995) 157. tinctions and formulations, that we cannot give shape or form to the Truth, but that we can only follow after it, and in his recognition that all our expressions and expo- sitions of the Truth are human attempts that fall far short of the Truth itself, so that far from resting content with what we have already done, we are driven on by respect for the Truth…18 Theological truth’s inherent modesty enables it to venture into public space, often in secular guise, to facilitate the truths of those who are not often heard. Political discourse falls back into the relativisation of non-derogable human rights most easily, when voices from the margins of society are not appropriately accommodated within public dialogue. South Africa has a remark- able record of failure as well as achievement in this area. To dwell on the positive: we know that over two million submissions were received during the writing of the 1995 Constitution, making this one of the most inclusive such processes ever. The Truth and Reconciliation Commission saturated middle class living rooms for two years with tales of sorrow and loss from the very margins of society, in a manner unprecedented internationally and making it impossible for any South African to claim with any credibility that he or she does not know that terrible things happened to others in the past. But how much do we really know about poverty today? How prevalent are the voices from the margins of society today? Everybody claims to speak on behalf of the poor, but who really does? How aware are we about the true extent of trauma associated with poverty; trauma that at times matches the trauma associated with gross human rights violations such as murder, rape, abduction and torture? Poverty, indeed, is daily torture. It is the murdering of dreams and personalities. It is the abduction from society, of millions of talented people. It is the rape of a nation. Can theology help to generate a national sense of urgency around poverty as did emerge around political change? Theological discourse needs to reflect teleological restlessness and pastoral solidarity, out- spoken urgency and self-effacing modesty. Is this not a contradiction? How are these seeming- ly conflicting traits to be reconciled? Can theology at once be forceful and self-effacing? To this end, it may be helpful to examine the nature of Christian truth-claims more closely, in order to understand how a nuanced reading of scripture can in fact yield truth-claims that are forceful, yet modest. Theology drinks from different fountains: scriptures, traditions of interpretation and praxis, contextual demands and dialogue with other faiths. Amongst these sources, theologians tend to prioritise scripture. Scripture is often held as the norm according to which other theological norms and sources are judged. Scripture, however, presents anything but simple, hegemonic norms. Containing a library of sixty-six books, produced over a period of more than 2000 years in many different parts of world, and recorded in an array of languages, it covers a historical epoch stretching back into the very origins of human memory. A litany of characters, narratives, perspectives, positions and ethical frameworks confronts the systematic reader of the Biblical canon. Yet, despite this indelible diversity, scriptures offer a number of longitudinal themes and per- spectives that cut across books and epochs. The identification of these synthetic concentrations of ideas is central to the task of systematic theology. Theology has, to this end, embraced the ‘scopic nature’ of scriptural hermeneutics. The sco- Social Justice and Theological Method 65 18 TF Torrance Karl Bath: An Introduction to his Early Theology, 1910-1931 (1960). 6 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E pus is a longitudinal theme or perspective singled out as the heart of the message and intention of all sixty-six books and serves to provide the singular hermeneutical frame within which the entire collection of scriptures needs to be interpreted and understood. A Christ-centric scopus, for example, focuses on the person and words of Jesus Christ as the prism through which all scriptures are understood. This is not an arbitrary hermeneutical strategy, but is rooted, so theologians believe, in the world presupposed by scripture itself. The Judeo-Christian world, in which the Bible has its roots, operates with a fluctuating, dynamic view of history. It is into this ever-changing arenas that Hebrew sees divine truth seeping, little by little, and with sensitivity to the fragile concep- tual frameworks that constitute human understanding. This hermeneutical strategy is shared by Christian theologies of many different persuasions, including some of the most dominant tra- ditions in South Africa. It differs from a fundamentalist approach where the very idea of a scopus is rejected. Seeing nuanced hermeneutical readings as undue human interference with the Divine Word, funda- mentalist theology claims to take each word, each passage and each narrative of the Bible as the literal, unchanging and eternal word of God. Yet there is an evident irony in the way this reading of scriptures plays itself out. Funda- mentalists achieve exactly what they seek to avoid. Their effort to ‘purify’ theology of human perspective in fact serves to obscure and entrench the pivotal role of subjectivity in the reading of scripture. Because it equates divine truth with the immediate, subjective encounter of read- ing the Bible (of whatever truth emerges there and then) the context within which the reading takes place becomes all-important. And yet, from a fundamentalist perspective, this impact of context is not only ignored, but vehemently denied. As a result, the dominant voices in a par- ticular context become the voice of God. The result: fundamentalist truth-claims render theol- ogy more relative, not less. The Truth With Which There Can Be No Argument, is a truth that emanates from intensely private, deeply parochial positions of leaders powerful within their own groups of followers, but usually situated on the fringe of society. The ideological opposite to fundamentalism is radical relativism,19 where theology relinquish- es any pretence to truth that is not in every respect cultural and contextual. Scripture as a whole loses priority and competes, on equal footing, with all other sources. In this approach there is a real danger that theology will lose its distinctive voice and become just another weak mirage – a second-hand version – of other disciplines such as sociology, anthropology or poetry. Ironically the same danger of arbitrariness confronts the relativist theologian and his funda- mentalist counterpart. To relativists, any hint of ‘truth’, any trace of the universal or transcen- dent, is denied. Yet, in the place of the Divine, human subjectivity assumes the central position. When opinion, speculation and perspective are acknowledged as the only social currency, power once again takes the place of argumentation. Dialogue always presupposes moving towards some form of ‘truth’ – inter-subjective and provisional as it may be. But when this pos- sibility falls away completely, dialogue collapses into rhetoric of the most cynical kind. Even Foucault reminds us never to give up our quest for truth. In the Nietzschean context of radical relativism, whoever possesses the largest megaphone (or gun) normally wins the argument. The advantages of a more sophisticated, scopus-defined hermeneutics now become clearer: 19 See for example TJJ Altizer The Genesis of God – A Theological Genealogy (1993); MCE Taylor Erring: A Postmodern A/theology (1984); D Cupitt The Long-legged Fly (1987); D Griffen Primordial Truth and Postmodern Theology (1989). See also G Ward (ed) The Postmodern God: A Theological Reader (1998). Admitting to the perspectival nature of all theological truth, makes for more transparent and honest dialogue where presuppositions can be voiced and influenced. Admitting to perspectival readings of theological sources opens the door for contesting inter- pretations, and limits the possibility for hegemony and tyranny in the name of God’s truth. Scopus-hermeneutics also helps to negotiate the vast historical and contextual differences and even paradoxes found between different scriptural passages. It allows for progression of truth and insight and can therefore identify certain prescriptions as time-bound and culture-rel- ative whilst others can consistently be identified as culture-relativising. Scopus-hermeneutics counters radical relativism and proclaims, in an era of rampant nihilist consumerism, the elusive presence of transcendent truth. Scopus-hermeneutics thus creates the conditions for genuine inter-subjectivity – the proper breeding ground for theological truth. This is a position between the tyranny of absolute, objec- tive truth with which there can be no argument, and the different tyranny of radical subjective relativism; a space where the possibility of argumentation falls away. ‘Knowing-in-part’ is the forte of good theology. The science that finds its orientation in the face of God can only see its truth as ‘a poor reflection as in a mirror’. If theology knows any- thing, it is that truth finally lies beyond us. It is not a carrier of truth, but a pointer, self-effac- ing, to divine words that can never be repeated, to divine presence that remains hidden and to a divine community that remains scattered. It is therefore, in its best moments, a troublemaker in the company of those ‘who know’: pos- ing questions, unravelling arguments and exposing those voices of the marginalised and maligned not often heard. This is what it is called to do. When things go wrong, and theology tries, like a slightly awkward child, to ‘fit in with the rest’, to develop certain knowledge and pose proudly in the conceptual designer wear of its age, it invariably comes to grief. Like the awkward child, when it struggles to assert itself, it usually does so with too much force. Theology is a tricky business. (C) HOPE Up to now human development and the quest for justice have been used virtually interchange- ably, as if the one implies the other. Of course, this is not always the case. Not all development is just. Development is mostly inherently ambiguous and its impact on humanity has positive as well as negative effects. Social development is an unstoppable reality, that proceeds with or without moral input. Economic development is also a self-propelling phenomenon, operating with or without moral guidance. Justice calls for a certain kind of development, associated to some extent with integrated visions of development presented by Amartya Sen and others mentioned above. This human- focused development, aiming to restore human dignity, is in my view central to the Biblical call of justice. There is considerable difference of opinion about how successful such development efforts can be expected to be in the long term. Some claim that South Africa will remain, certainly for the foreseeable future, fundamentally unequal. Others predict a speedy eradication of poverty, with social services up and running within the decade; coinciding with a proliferation of employment, improved education and growing industrial output. Who should be believed – the pessimists or the optimists? Theologies that believe the pessimists offer options for utopian withdrawal with strong dosages of what Karl Marx would call ‘opium for the masses’; feel-good, emotionally soothing Social Justice and Theological Method 67 6 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E fellowship where people gather to anticipate reward in the after-life. In this life justice will always be but a dream. Theologies that believe the optimists tend to align with activist groups in society who often are radically critical of mainstream society and post-apartheid policy decisions, but who are often short on engaged, constructive proposals for change. What does theology base its hope on? A negative historical prognosis typically coincides with an emphasis on human depravation and sin. A positive prognosis typically emerges from an emphasis on the inherent goodness of people, on some concept of the image of God that all people carry. Importantly, what one expects from human development, what we dare hope, is largely based on these anthropological foundations. Anthropology is therefore worthy of special focus. Formulating a Christian anthropology has been the aim of countless volumes of theology, but it remains a highly complex task – not least in the context of a transitional society emerging from oppression and violence. Social change of this magnitude and depth typically gives rise to deeply complex anthropological phenomena.20 Classic theological debates, ranging on the spectrum outlined above, traditionally paid a lot of attention to the epistemological foundations of anthropology. This has often resulted in the ques- tioning of the relationship between divine revelation, theology and anthropology. Can God be known in and through the human spirit, or can the human spirit only be known in the light of Di- vine Self-revelation? The former position, a classic tenet of liberal theology, was described by Lud- wig Feuerbach as nothing else than a projection of the human self against the screen of eternity: Religion, at least the Christian, is the relation of man to himself, or more correctly to his own nature… The divine being is nothing else than the human being, or rather, the human nature purified, freed from the limits of the individual man made objective… All attributes of the divine nature are, therefore, attributes of the human nature. 21 For Feuerbach, theology is anthropology. Such reductionism invited sharp reactions, not least from Karl Barth and his Neo-Orthodox colleagues early in the 20th century. They insisted that theological anthropology could never exist as an independent subject. Humans could never know themselves without prior knowledge of the Divine. In fact, without the Divine, the human being is not even an object of knowledge. To them, anthropology is an extension of theological descriptions of divine revelation. The resolution of this debate lies outside the scope of this essay. Whilst acknowledging the different positions, the key question for us is whether this and other theological debates pro- vide us with substantive anthropological insights, however derived, that could help guide and stimulate responsible efforts towards social justice. Perhaps it will suffice to say that following Barth in his epistemological agnosticism (we can 20 Victims of human rights violations frequently do not have the emotional strength to face deep change or ambitious development programmes. Formerly disadvantaged citizens often suffer from a lack of confidence and skills. Beneficiaries of past injustice often feel a sense of moral condemnation and mourn a loss of priv- ilege or power. They either feel unable to contribute to the new order or take refuge in a secluded, priva- tised environment – not infrequently sponsored by theologies of a different nature. Some ex-combatants fail to be integrated into society long after the battles are over. They often become dependent on the welfare, or resort to violence and crime. Perpetrators of gross human rights atrocities may seek to subvert the new order, to avoid prosecution or consider ways to pursue violence through other means. They may also sim- ply withdraw. 21 L Feuerbach The Essence of Christianity (1989, first published in 1841) at 14. never fully know Divine truth) does not necessarily imply that we follow him in his extreme anthropological assumptions, where the very possibility of a contact point in the human spirit with the Divine is vehemently denied. It is possible, I contend, to hold onto Barth’s epistemological modesty but at the same time develop some form of positive anthropology, perhaps shaped by the concept of the universal image of God. Created in God’s image, people all carry the ability to and propensity for rela- tionships. When God’s word goes out into the universe, it finds a response in kind only at one point: the human spirit. Created to be able to respond to the words from God, and thus to enter into a relationship with the Divine, human beings carry an inherent, indestructible ability to relate. Even the most inhumane individuals never lose this capacity. They may deny it, abuse it, or even actively seek to subvert it, but they cannot destroy it. This positive assertion about human nature is a centre piece of many forms of Christian theology and remains the starting point of many prominent and sophisticated theories of human nature. I use the word ‘sophisti- cated’, precisely because it creates a nuanced view of human nature as neither totally depraved, nor innately good. The ability to relate forms the basis of firm hope for progress, but since this capacity can clearly be abused, it is no automatic guarantee of progress or justice. However, because it is an indestructible reality it cannot be ignored either. It continues to prompt and nudge human society towards the building of relations across boundaries. This implies that all people, in the developed and the developing worlds alike, share a basic propen- sity for entering into relationships with others because they all share in the image of God. (At the same time, of course, the dark side, the self-isolating apartheid-side of human nature pulls and pushes in the opposite direction.) The mere possibility of progress, structurally and universally given as a constituent part of human nature, is cause for hope, albeit nuanced hope. No progress is assured. No outcome is guaranteed, but the possibility to progress towards a more just world is a structural anthropo- logical reality. So, what may South Africans hope for? We may hope for more progress, deeper solidarity and more overt social justice. History is open with these and other possibilities. We may also, with good cause, fear failure. The rational response would be to put as much effort as possible into the creation of a more humane, more dignified society, knowing that this corresponds to ancient and modern conceptions of what humans are all about. The outcome is not yet deter- mined, but there are grounds for hope and enough reason to commit ourselves fully to the proj- ect of justice for all. (D) JUSTICE Human rights discourses are often suspected of Western bias, a kind of latter day colonialism based on European (or Enlightenment) chauvinism. It is becoming clearer that, human rights discourses, to have genuine universal appeal and legitimacy, need to demonstrate, not least in contexts of deep suffering, some understanding of concrete conditions and contextual realities. In more practical terms, the abstract individualism at the root of rights discourses needs to be complemented with insights derived from collective identities, shaped by historical, cultural and religious practises and beliefs. The postulation of universal equality, certainly in the founding fathers of theories of natural rights, such as Locke and Hobbes, was built on the identification of similarities in people the world over. This led to the gradual devaluation of contextual differences, a reality that is now gaining prominence again. Social Justice and Theological Method 69 7 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E So-called ‘thin universals’, the idea that human rights can be formulated as general ‘one-lin- ers’ encapsulating on a human right true of all place and all people, feed (necessarily so) off strongly reduced, abstracted meanings. Indispensable as these formulations have become, they fail to do justice to the social dynamics of different contexts the world over. One example may be taken from the Hebrew Scriptures, where individual responsibility is conceived as fundamentally social in nature. In this context, social rights are not some nice afterthought, but indeed the precondition for the achievement of even the most basic individ- ual rights. ‘Thicker’ versions of human rights have a better chance of achieving lasting appeal in differ- ent contexts, than simplistically abstracted and applied individual rights, but one has to be care- ful not to compromise the essential message of freedom, equality and security for all. Maurice Cranston contends that the expansion of the term ‘human right’ to incorporate social consid- erations all but renders the term meaningless. Cranston describes a human right as a ‘form of moral right’ attributable to ‘all people at all times in all situations’.22 ‘A right differs from an ideal, in that it represents something that can, and from a moral point of view must, be respect- ed here and now’, says Cranston. ‘A rights claim is a powerful demand for action’, adds Donnely.23 A right is only a right if it has as collorative a duty. That is, a right that does not imply a duty to respond to the claim cannot be called a right. In short, human rights are not a wish-list thought out in splendid isolation, but a limited, sharply focused set of universally enforcable claim-rights. This position offers important insights not to be lost in our haste to accommodate contex- tual realities. Human rights would have lost its essence if watered down, or ‘contextualised’ to the point where they would condone repressive social hierarchies or regimes that demand absolute submission. At the same time rights discourses need to learn to speak to people in their particular settings, as whole, integrated individuals with more than legal, civic or political needs, but with equally pressing economic, social and environmental needs. Moreover, they operate in systems of thought and meaning that may substantially enrich human rights con- ceptions of equality and freedom. One such system of thought, itself deeply diverse the world over, is Christian theology. Christianity holds the incarnation of truth not only dear, but as the sacred way that God revealed His Universal Truth to the human race – through incarnation into the concrete living conditions of Palestine 2000 years ago. At the same time the transcendent message was not lost, but in fact emphasised. From here it is but a small conceptual step to recognise the fundamental importance that the Bible places on justice for the whole human being, in all her dimensions and in her concrete context. Theology is a potential source of the grammar and contents of thicker versions of jus- tice that transcends the narrow (but important) categories of Enlightenment thought. This makes theology and law ideal dialogue partners. Charles Villa-Vicencio argues that law provides a sense of order, integrity and purpose to society. Theology, on the other hand, pro- vides an incentive to transform law, as John Witte says ‘the telos, it needs to move forward.’ Without religion law decays into empty formalism. Without law, religion decays into shallow spiritualism. Part of the crisis of our law today is that it has become formalistic, undirected, lacking vision. It lost its religious dimension. Part of the crises has of our religion is that it has 22 M Cranston, ‘Human Rights, Real and Supposed’ in DD Raphael (ed) Political Theory and the Rights of Man (1967) at 51-53. 23 J Donnely Universal Human Rights in Theory and Practice (1989) at 10f. become spiritualistic, disorganised, diluted, lacking in discipline. It has lost its legal dimen- sion.’ 24 To stimulate a sense of urgency and a collective understanding of what justice in its fullest sense would mean is the task of theology. Making sure we do it orderly and fairly is the task of law. V Conclusion The essay aims to illustrate that truthful theology cannot ignore its public responsibility. Its rest- less reaching out to people, most notably the poor and marginalised, its modest truth-claims, its nuanced but firm hope, and its irrepressible quest for justice in all its dimensions propels theological discourse into the public sphere time and time again. Theology cannot avoid going public, but needs to do so responsibly. The road to justice has never been clearer. At the same time much remains to be done. Theology can provide motivation, fuel and stamina for the journey to justice by providing vision, urgency and purpose to development initiatives. For this to happen, theology would have to develop the analytical capacity to understand the current social and economic challenges and to move beyond mere sloganism and rhetoric towards concrete, constructive proposals that engage both the Christian message and the his- torical realities in South Africa. This is at once a journey out of the laager of theological discourse but also, and I sought to emphasise this here, a journey back into the heart of what constitutes proper Christian theolo- gy. My view is that such a journey yields at least four insights that could act as guidelines on the way towards a more just, inclusive South Africa: The quest for justice for those who are excluded constitutes the essence of the restlessness which characterises theology that remains true to its Source – the grace of God. God’s truth remains present in our world, but in a subtle, ‘hidden’ way, mediating the voic- es of the poor and marginalized. The image of God in people forms the basis of social hope. This possibility of progress is cause for hope. Yet it remains a nuanced hope. No progress is assured. Theology’s concern with justice in all its dimensions prompts it to continue to engage other disciplines such as law, equally indispensable to the cause. It provides a constant reminder of the importance of incarnating universal human rights dicta into the concrete living conditions of the poor, the disenfranchised and the voiceless. Social Justice and Theological Method 71 24 J Witte ‘The Study of Law and Religion: An Apologia and Agenda’ (1988) Fall Ministry and Mission at 14:4. A Not so Simple Justice: Frank Michelman on Social Rights, 1969 – Present* W I L L I A M E F O R B AT H Lloyd M Bentsen Chair in Law, Professor of History, University of Texas at Austin I Introduction (A) THE CONSTITUTION IN THE YEAR 2020 Periods of no power, Charles Black once wrote, are periods for ‘reformation of thought,’1 for thinking anew and ‘thinking large’ about visions, goals, and strategies. In constitutional law, as elsewhere, liberals and progressives are out of power. We are on the defensive and are pressed to think small: criticizing countless decisions; defending doctrines and precepts under attack; advancing modest proposals, each apparently a tub on its own bottom, guided by no larger con- stitutional vision. We cannot afford to overlook the need to think large, about the constitutional bases on which we — or our students — will build anew, when the opportunity comes. We must take a leaf from our adversaries. In the late 1970s and early 1980s, when their ideas were wildly out of tune with judicial doctrine and mainstream political and academic opinion, right-wing constitutional thinkers set about crafting an alternate account of our constitutional past, an alternate vision of our future, and a cogent set of ideas about the way constitutional law should unfold in every key area of their concerns. In the late 1980s, right-wing constitu- tional lawyers in the Reagan Justice Department produced a remarkable 185-page document entitled The Constitution in the Year 2000;2 and the rest, as they say, is history.3 And while history does not repeat itself, it rhymes. So, we need to begin writing The Constitution in the Year 2020. One important chapter in that book will address the problems of poverty and economic inequality. Today’s Supreme Court tells us that the Constitution affords no protection against desperate want, nor does it confer on Americans any other ‘affir- * Portions of this article draw substantially from WE Forbath ‘‘Constitutional Welfare Rights’: A History, Critique and Reconstruction’ (2001) 69 Fordham LR 1821. This article first appeared as William Forbath ‘A not so Simple Justice: Frank Michelman on Social Rights, 1969 – Present‘ (2004) 39 Tulsa Law Review 597-638 and is reprinted here with the kind permission of W Forbath and Tulsa Law Review. 1 CL Black ‘Further Reflections on the Constitutional Justice of Livelihood’ (1986) 86 Col LR 1103 at 1115. 2 Official Legislative Policy Report to the Attorney General: The Constitution in the Year 2000: Choices Ahead in Constitutional Interpretation (US Dept of Justice 1988) (available at ). 3 See DE Johnsen ‘Ronald Reagan and the Rehnquist Court on Congressional Power: Presidential Influences on Constitutional Change’ (2003) 78 Ind LJ 363 (discussing the history and impact of the report). mative rights’ to such basic goods as minimally adequate education or a realistic opportunity to make a livelihood.4 These ‘social rights’ are features of most of the world’s constitutions;5 and many prominent constitutional courts have been elaborating and (some boldly, some gin- gerly) enforcing them, some with explicit textual bases, some without.6 Today’s conservatives would have us think that social rights and the solicitude for them among the world’s great courts are foreign to American constitutional experience. That is wrong.7 What is true, though, is that the current Court’s hostility partly reflects the broader disillusionment with the New Deal and the welfare state, as these are understood in the US polity today. A key aspect of the liberal/progressive project today lies in reinvigorating the old convictions that all Americans are entitled to a modest share in the nation’s wealth, to protection against desperate want, and to the opportunity to make a decent livelihood. There is substantial disagreement and uncertain- ty about what kinds of reforms or even what programmatic vision is best suited to carrying for- ward these commitments in the early twenty-first century; but they remain a defining feature of the nation we believe the Constitution promises to promote and redeem. Frank Michelman on Social Rights 73 4 See DeShaney v Winnebago County Dept of Soc Services 489 US 189 196 (1989). 5 See G Casper ‘Changing Concepts of Constitutionalism: 18th to 20th Century’ (1989) S Ct Rev 311 at 318- 21; M Glendon ‘Rights in Twentieth-Century Constitutions’ (1992) 59 U Chi LR 519 at 523-24 (noting the anomalous nature of the United States Constitution for its lack of affirmative welfare obligations, as com- pared to the constitutions of other liberal democracies); A Ben-Bassat & M Dahan ‘Social Rights in the Constitution and in Practice’ (Hebrew U of Jerusalem School of Public Policy Working Paper No 05-03 May 2003) (available at ) (examining the constitutional commitment to social rights in sixty-eight countries). 6 For recent comparative accounts of judicial enforcement of constitutional social rights, see M Tushnet ‘Strong Rights, Weak Courts’ (2004) 82 Tex LR 1895; M Tushnet ‘State Action, Social Welfare Rights, and the Judicial Role: Some Comparative Observations’ (2002) 3 Chi J Intl L 435; KL Scheppele ‘A Realpolitik Theory of Social Rights’ (2004) 82 Tex LR 1921. For the reflections of an architect of the South African Constitution’s social rights provisions, now a justice of that nation’s Constitutional Court, see Justice A Sachs ‘Enforcement of Social and Economic Rights’ (Speech at London School Econ Feb 27 2003) (available at ); see also the rich collection of research papers in Community Law Center, Realizing Socio-Economic Rights in South Africa: Progress and Challenges (accessed Apr 24 2004). 7 In the 1960s and early 1970s, the Supreme Court came extremely close to recognizing such rights in a series of statutory and constitutional cases which produced remedial schemes comparable to several under con- struction abroad. The Supreme Court’s personnel and the nation’s political climate changed before a jurisprudence of social citizenship took root. See WE Forbath ‘Lincoln, the Declaration, and the ‘Grisly, Undying Corpse of States’ Rights’: History, Memory, and Imagination in the Constitution of a Southern Liberal’ (2004) Geo LJ 709; WE Forbath ‘‘Constitutional Welfare Rights’: A History, Critique and Reconstruction’ (2001) 69 Fordham LR 1821 at 1823; infra text accompanying notes 28-61. On the long history of robust social rights discourse in the legislative and public political domains of constitutional argument and interpretation in America, see WE Forbath ‘‘Caste, Class, and Equal Citizenship’’ (1999) 98 Mich LR 1 [hereinafter Forbath ‘Caste, Class, and Equal Citizenship’] and WE Forbath ‘The New Deal Constitution’ in Exile’ (2001) 51 Duke LJ 165 [hereinafter Forbath ‘The New Deal Constitution’]. It was the rights discourse of New Deal and 1940s America that inspired the social rights provisions of many con- stitutions around the globe. See CR Sunstein ‘The Second Bill of Rights: The Last Great Speech of Franklin Delano Roosevelt and America’s Unfinished Pursuit of Freedom’ (prelim draft 26 July 2003) (copy on file with Tulsa Law Review) (noting the influence on post-World War II constitution-making in Europe, Asia, and Africa, of Franklin Roosevelt’s ‘four freedoms’ and ‘second Bill of Rights,’ and of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, which Eleanor Roosevelt and others crafted to reflect FDR’s ‘four freedoms’ and second ‘Bill’). For a more sustained discussion, see M Glendon A World Made New: Eleanor Roosevelt and the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (2001). 7 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E So, the authors of The Constitution in the Year 2020 will have to ponder anew whether, why, and how the Constitution and (a separate question) judicially enforced constitutional law should be interpreted to safeguard these commitments. When they do so, they will find no bet- ter interlocutor than Frank Michelman. No one has thought and written more deeply about the question of constitutional social rights. Spanning almost four decades, Michelman’s work offers several of the most important approaches to the problems of poverty and economic inequality in the precincts of American constitutionalism. In this brief essay, I will engage some of Michelman’s most important contributions. Partly, I’ll do so from the perspective of constitutional theory, partly, from the vantage point of an his- torian. Only by situating our past thinking in the context of the social movements and politi- cal moments that shaped that thinking can we appreciate its distinctive insights and blind spots. So, I will situate Michelman’s classic essays on constitutional welfare rights in the context of the welfare rights movement and its distinctive possibilities and constraints. This contextual account will set the stage for a textual argument, a critical reading of Michelman’s reading of Rawls’s epoch-making 1971 book, A Theory of Justice.8 Michelman, I’ll suggest, overlooks the extent to which Rawls is critical of welfare state liberalism in favor of a more ambitious con- stitutional political economy, which Rawls dubs ‘property-owning democracy.’ From Rawls, Michelman turned in the 1980s to republicanism, and a key aspect of Michelman’s enormous- ly influential contributions to the republican revival was his republican treatment of the dis- tributive dimension of constitutional property claims. Michelman reads republicanism as he reads Rawls; both imply constitutional welfare rights. But the republican tradition is largely hostile to welfare rights; its distributive norms point to the distribution of material opportuni- ties for self support and ‘independence.’ Welfare rights, I’ll suggest, are better seen as a critique of this distributive dimension of republicanism than as an implication of it. Happily, these historical and theoretical criticisms are part of a present conversation with Michelman about social rights.9 And as a round in that conversation, this essay is gratefully written, taking up not only Rawls and republicanism, but also more recent work by Michelman on social rights and constitutional democracy. (B) DIALOGUES WITH FRANK MICHELMAN: FIRST CITIZEN OF THE REPUBLIC OF LETTERS I say gratefully written because, as Jefferson might have put it, Frank Michelman is a first citizen of the republic of letters, and there is no more generous, careful, and imaginative reader in the re- public. He reads and engages with the works of fellow citizens everywhere, and every work is made deeper and clearer after Michelman’s light has shined on it, exploring unmapped distinctions and uncharted implications and resonances, leaving the work richer and the author gladly indebted. What’s more, Michelman’s style of engagement instantiates a dialogical ethics and helps make 8 J Rawls A Theory of Justice (1971). 9 See Forbath ‘Constitutional Welfare Rights’ (note 7 above) at 1825-27; FI Michelman ‘The Constitution, Social Rights, and Liberal Political Justification’ (2003) 1 Intl J Const L 13 at 25-34 (available at ) [hereinafter Michelman ‘Constitution and Social Rights’] (discussing Forbath’s conception of ‘social citizenship’ rights); FI Michelman ‘‘Democracy-Based Resistance’ to a Constitutional Right of Social Citizenship: A Comment on Forbath’ (2001) 69 Fordham LR 1893 [hereinafter Michelman Democracy Based-Resistance] (responding to Forbath ‘Constitutional Welfare Rights’ (note 7 above)). him an exemplar of some of the ideas his own writings explore. Compare, for just a moment, Michelman’s manner of reading with that of one his most important interlocutors: Jürgen Habermas. Habermas reads, critiques, and appropriates, trimming off what doesn’t fit and putting the useful parts to work in the ever-enlarging Habermasian machinery. Michelman’s mode of appropriation is different, more respectful and also more provisional, more in the way of dialogue than system-building. Michelman is more inclined to put the insights of one school of thought to work in order to reveal the blindness of another. He seems most comfortable in-between. Consider, for example, the controversies between pragmatists like Rorty and neo-Kantian liberals like Habermas.10 Inside law schools and elsewhere, it’s common to find scholars who seem to think that Rorty or someone else has delivered the knock-out punch to Habermas and his kind, or vice versa. As finely and shrewdly as anyone, Michelman can turn a pragmatist cri- tique of Habermas’s categorical distinctions ethics versus morality; the good versus the right; the principles of justice versus their application, and so on.11 But in contrast to those who line up in one of the two camps, Michelman seems to feel the pull of the neo-Kantian enterprise as strongly as the counter-tug of pragmatism. And he brings them into revealing contact, into a sustained dialogue that Michelman’s work enacts. Another instance of this same dialogical in-betweenness in the work of Frank Michelman is in-between liberalism and critical legal studies (CLS), which was a rare enough position, I believe, in the heated politics of Harvard Law School in the 1970s and 1980s. I don’t know how this translated in terms of faculty politics, but intellectually, Frank was distinctive: carry- ing on the liberal problematic justice, justifiability, justiciability, judicial review, and democra- cy while at the same time opening the doors of that discourse to fresh blasts of CLS and femi- nist insight.12 From the 1980s, however, we must hasten back to the 1960s, and follow this lib- eral man of the left back to his engagement with the War on Poverty. II Why Welfare?: The War on Poverty and the Welfare Rights Movement Michelman’s famous 1969 Harvard Foreword, ‘On Protecting the Poor through the Fourteenth Amendment,’13 was a product of what Michelman called the ‘great War’ in a material as well Frank Michelman on Social Rights 75 10 Among Rorty’s most important works are R Rorty Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (1980); R Rorty Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (1989); and R Rorty Truth and Progress (1998). Habermas’s important works include: J Habermas The Theory of Communicative Action (1987); J Habermas The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity: Twelve Lectures (1987); J Habermas, The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere: An Inquiry into a Category of Bourgeois Society (1989); and J Habermas Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy (1996). For a law professor’s read- ing of Rorty, see JW Singer ‘The Player and the Cards: Nihilism and Legal Theory’ (1984) 94 Yale LJ 1; and of Habermas, see WE Forbath ‘Habermas’s Constitution: A History, Guide, and Critique’ (1998) 23 L & Soc Inquiry 969. 11 See eg FI Michelman ‘The Problem of Constitutional Interpretive Disagreement: Can “Discourse of Application” Help?’ in M Aboulafai et al Habermas and Pragmatism (2002) 113-39; FI Michelman ‘Family Quarrel’ (1996) 17 Cardozo LR 1163 [hereinafter Michelman ‘Family Quarrel’] (Symposium on Habermas on Law and Democracy). 12 See eg FI Michelman ‘Justification (and Justifiability) of Law in a Contradictory World’ in J R Pennock & J W Chapman eds NOMOS XXVIII: Justification (1986) 71, 79-81; MJ Radin & FI Michelman ‘Pragmatist and Poststructuralist Critical Legal Practice’ (1991) 139 U Pa LR 1019. 13 FI Michelman ‘Foreword: On Protecting the Poor through the Fourteenth Amendment’ (1969) 83 Harv LR 7. 7 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E as a moral sense; we learn in its acknowledgments that the article ‘was prepared . . . with funds provided by The US Office of Economic Opportunity.’14 The Office of Economic Opportunity was the command center of the Johnson administration’s War on Poverty. It created Com- munity Action Agencies, and alongside them, it created the Legal Services Organization (LSO). In addition to law offices in the inner cities, the LSO funded a handful of law school-based back-up centers, including Harvard’s, with which Michelman was associated.15 A great portion of the work of these agencies and inner-city law offices involved ‘getting poor people to apply for welfare and attacking the social and legal barriers to their receiving it. Centuries-old restric- tions were broken down by a combination of civic unrest and federally funded organizing and litigation.’16 (A) WHY ‘WELFARE’? Constitutional scholars see the origins of the constitutional welfare rights idea in the Warren Court’s Fourteenth Amendment case law and the Court’s new solicitude toward the nation’s poor. But why was ‘welfare’ the terrain on which 1960s community activists, federal policy- makers, and legal advocates and scholars like Michelman came to wage their ‘War on Poverty’? The answer lies in the constraints and opportunities created by inherited statutory, institution- al, and ideological frameworks—the results of the victories and defeats of earlier efforts to forge a more substantive and ‘social’ array of citizenship rights. Put baldly, it was the defeat of key New Deal reforms in the 1930s and 1940s that deprived 1960s advocates of broader channels down which to try to nudge the Court’s solicitude. FDR’s famous ‘second Bill of Rights’ set forth not welfare but decent work and universal social insur- ance as the economic rights essential to free and equal citizenship in the twentieth century, but Roosevelt’s vaunted right to decent work met defeat at the hands of Jim Crow and the Solid South. Measures instituting rights to full employment, decent work, and social provision for all Americans enjoyed broad support; yet they expired in the New Deal Congress, doomed by the hammer lock that southern Democratic lawmakers enjoyed by dint of numbers, seniority, and key committee chairs. Hailing from an impoverished region with a populist tradition, most southern Democrats in Congress were staunch supporters of the New Deal until the late 1930s. In exchange for their support, however, they insisted on decentralized state administration and local standard setting of all labor measures, and they demanded that key bills exclude the main categories of southern labor. By allying with northern Republicans, or by threatening to do so, they stripped all the main pieces of New Deal legislation of any design or provision that threat- ened the separate southern labor market and its distinctive meld of class and caste relations, its racial segmentation, and its low wages. Keeping blacks dependent on local labor markets and poor relief was the principal reason for the segmented and caste-ridden system of social provi- sion and labor rights bequeathed by the New Deal.17 A quarter-century later, this system underpinned a fairly robust private welfare state of job security, pensions, and health insurance for organized workers in core sectors of the industrial 14 Idem at 7. 15 See idem. 16 Forbath ‘Constitutional Welfare Rights’ (note 7 above) at 1842. For a more detailed account, see idem at 1838-66. 17 I develop this historical argument in Forbath ‘Constitutional Welfare Rights’ (note 7 above) at 1835-45. economy. But that meld of public and private rights excluded most African Americans, whose anger exploded in all the large cities of the North, where millions of southern blacks had moved over the preceding decades to escape Jim Crow and rural unemployment. For them, public assistance, primarily Aid to Families with Dependent Children (AFDC), stood as the sole fed- eral protection against poverty. (B) AID TO FAMILIES WITH DEPENDENT CHILDREN Created by the Social Security Act of 1935,18 originally titled Aid to Dependent Children (ADC) and renamed AFDC in the 1950s, the federal ADC descended from the state-based Mothers’ Pensions programs of the early twentieth century, themselves a modern variant of the age-old practice of giving poor relief to ‘deserving widows.’19 Like the other branches of the Social Security Act, ADC was drafted to propitiate the South. So the states could determine AFDC benefits levels, and local administrators enjoyed vast discretion in making eligibility determinations.20 Local administrators used that discretion to buttress low-wage labor markets and to exercise other kinds of disciplinary power. In the South, for example, AFDC officials deemed poor black women ‘employable mothers,’ and kept them off the rolls when their labor was needed in the cotton fields.21 More generally, AFDC payments in the South and indeed, in most states, were kept appreciably below official poverty levels. And throughout the nation, local administrators in the early 1960s still vigorously enforced man-in-the-house rules. Through home visits, unan- nounced nighttime searches, and the like, they removed from the rolls any woman found to be associating with a man, especially if he seemed to live in her house. In this fashion, welfare offi- cers prevented public monies from supporting ‘immoral women’ and ‘unsuitable mothers’; at the same time, they kept poor men from exploiting AFDC to escape any of the rigors of the low-wage labor market.22 Even for its target universe of impoverished single parent families, AFDC reached a tiny fraction of the whole. Most did not even apply; of those who did, pover- ty-stricken newcomers to a locale met almost certain rejection. Since colonial times, wayfaring paupers had been ‘warned off’ and forcibly excluded by the custodians of poor relief. Through- out the country, local custodians of AFDC carried on a modern version of this practice. In New York, for example, the very fact that you applied for welfare was presumptive proof of why you had come to the city. Rejected as ineligible, instead of welfare, you and your offspring got tick- ets on a Greyhound bus bound for home.23 It was this separate, decentralized, and deeply gendered benefits program, stamped with many of the centuries-old degradations of poor relief, that welfare rights organizers, advocates, and attorneys sought to transform into a dignifying right to a guaranteed income. Frank Michelman on Social Rights 77 18 49 Stat 620 (1935). 19 W Bell Aid to Dependent Children (1965) 9 (internal quotation omitted); M Ladd-Taylor Mother-Work: Women, Child Welfare, and the State, 1890-1930 (1994) at 136-66; S Michel Children’s Interests/Mothers’ Rights: The Shaping of America’s Child Care Policy (1999) 424-79; T Skocpol Protecting Soldiers and Mothers: The Political Origins of Social Policy in the United States (1992) 73-78. 20 Bell (note 9 above) at 33-34, 63-65, 76-79, 81-82, 108-09. 21 Idem at 34-35, 42, 55, 79, 83, 130, 138. 22 See idem at 4, 6, 80, 213 fn 7; R S Melnick Between the Lines: Interpreting Welfare Rights (1994) 57, 85- 90, 98, 121-22, 130. 23 See Melnick (note 22 above) at 77. 7 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E (C) THE WELFARE RIGHTS MOVEMENT Fostered by the War on Poverty, the welfare rights movement of the 1960s was unique in the annals of American reform, and, as we’ll see, Michelman’s Foreword bears its stamp. Never before, or since, had poor African American women formed the rank and file of a nationally organized social movement. The movement departed from the vocabulary of reform bequeathed by earlier movements for social and economic justice. The welfare rights movement broke the links these older movements had forged between work and citizenship. Like them, the welfare rights movement claimed decent income as a right; unlike them, it did not tie this right to waged work. Generations of reformers had constructed their ideals of economic justice for the poor and working classes in a gendered fashion, around the workingman-citizen; decent income and social provision belonged, as of right, to (presumptively white male) waged workers, and to their eco- nomic dependents. Poor black women had always toiled outside their homes,24 but they had never been welcomed into the producers’ republic of earlier reformers. By the 1960s poor black women had had enough experience in urban labor markets to know that decent jobs were hard to find, and enough experience with workfare programs to think them coercive and demeaning. Theirs was a consumers’ republic.25 ‘”Give Us Credit for Being Americans,” read the [National Welfare Rights Organization’s (NWRO)] placards demanding Sears credit cards for welfare recipients.’26 For them a guaranteed adequate income was an unconditional citizenship right, essential to equal respect and an appropriate touchstone of equality in an affluent America. This rupture with the past was both a strength and a limit of the NWRO. It highlighted the coercive and gendered aspects of older employment-based ideals of economic and distributive justice. Gaining welfare as a matter of right would relieve unwarranted suffering and indignity. But it would not do enough to help poor African Americans make their way into a shared social destiny of work and opportunity. Without other enabling rights to training, decent work, and childcare, welfare rights risked modernizing the badges and incidents of racial and economic subordination instead of abolishing them. Mimicking AFDC also led to the absence of poor men in a movement that claimed to represent the nation’s poor and their needs. It led to a rights rhetoric that downplayed the disappearance of decently paid unskilled industrial jobs from the nation’s old industrial regions and center cities.27 Welfare rights risked saddling poor African Americans with a new variant of the old racist imagery of blacks as idle and dependent. But the NWRO played the hand that was dealt it. Perhaps only by mimicking AFDC and building on its provisions could a social movement of the poorest, most powerless Americans have been forged. By making AFDC-eligible women the movement’s constituents, welfare rights organizers had something to offer the rank and file, and the rank and file developed a sense of efficacy and entitlement by gaining their demands from the nation’s welfare departments. Likewise, AFDC provided a basis for substantial gains through litigation. And the litigation, of course, is what inspired Michelman’s work, supporting and supported by the War on Poverty. The rupture between the older ideal of a right to decent work and the new ideal of a right to welfare also stamped Michelman’s work in ways we are about to explore. 24 See J Jones, Labor of Love, Labor of Sorrow: Black Women, Work, and the Family from Slavery to the Present (1985). 25 See Forbath ‘Constitutional Welfare Rights’ (note 7 above) at 1850-55. 26 Idem at 1851. 27 This was the social fact that civil rights leaders like Martin Luther King and Bayard Rustin highlighted and called on Congress to remedy as a necessary condition for the ‘full emancipation and equality of Negroes and the poor’: Forbath ‘‘Caste, Class, and Equal Citizenship’’ (note 7 above) at 87. III Frank Michelman’s Constitutional ‘War on Poverty’ (A) WELFARE RIGHTS IN THE COURTS Constitutional scholars today remember Goldberg v Kelly,28 Shapiro v Thompson,29 and a handful of other constitutional decisions bearing on welfare rights, but we tend to forget the hundreds of statutory cases that dramatically broadened eligibility standards and went a remarkable distance toward transforming a grant-in-aid to the states to be administered as meanly as local officialdom saw fit, into a no-strings and no-stigmas national right to welfare.30 These cases saw the Supreme Court and the lower federal courts undertake dozens of remark- able doctrinal innovations and boldly revisionary readings of the statutory text and history.31 The whole push of these developments was reflected in the courts’ repeated insistence that pub- lic assistance for all the nation’s needy was, in the Supreme Court’s words, a ‘basic commit- ment,’ not charity or largess, but a right. The Court recognized a private right of action against the state welfare agencies that admin- istered AFDC,32 revising or ignoring jurisdictional rules that seemed to bar the way,33 and spurning the conventional remedy of federal funding cut-offs in favor of injunctive relief.34 Above all, the Court shoved aside the view, shared by judges, welfare administrators, and mem- bers of Congress alike for the first thirty years of AFDC’s existence, that under AFDC states had authority to run their own programs, imposing such conditions and standards as they chose, subject only to a handful of limitations listed in the federal statute.35 State and local autonomy over the administration of federal relief had been the southern Democrats’ sina qua non, and, as we know, the architects of the 1935 Social Security Act, of which AFDC was a part, had provided it. In place of the wide berth they had left for state discretion, the Court cre- ated a new presumption: ‘a heavy burden lay on state lawmakers and administrators to justify any exclusion, test or condition that deviated from the principle of “actual need”’.36 LSO attor- neys persuaded the federal courts to embrace this presumption and to wield it against hundreds of state rules excluding would-be AFDC recipients.37 Within the federal statutory categories, the federal courts in the 1960s and early 1970s proved extraordinarily willing to treat welfare under AFDC as a right of all needy individuals. The leading statutory case was King v Smith,38 in which the Court struck down an Alabama Frank Michelman on Social Rights 79 28 397 US 254 (1970). 29 394 US 618 (1969). 30 Forbath ‘Constitutional Welfare Rights’ (note 7 above) at 1862. 31 Idem at 1863. 32 See RB Stewart & CR Sunstein ‘Public Programs and Private Rights’ (1982) 95 Harv LR 1195 at 1289-90. 33 See eg Hagans v Lavine 415 US 528 534-35 fn 5 537 541-42 (1974); King v Smith 392 US 309 312 fn 3 (1968). 34 See Melnick (note 22 above) at 50. 35 See Bell (note 19 above) at 50; M Derthick The Influence of Federal Grants: Public Assistance in Massachusetts (1970); WJ Cohen ‘The Social Security Act of 1935: Reflections Fifty Years Later’ in The Report of the Committee on Economic Security of 1935 at 3 (50th anniversary ed Natl Conf on Soc Welfare 1985). 36 Forbath ‘Constitutional Welfare Rights’ (note 7 above) at 1859. 37 See SE Lawrence The Poor in Court: The Legal Services Program and Supreme Court Decision Making (1990) 123-48; generally MF Davis Brutal Need: Lawyers and The Welfare Rights Movement, 1960-1973 (1993). 38 392 US 309 (1968). 8 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E man-in-the-house eligibility rule issued by Governor George Wallace in 1964. Under Wallace’s rule, Alabama had dropped 16,000 children ninety percent of them black from its welfare roll. The three-judge court below had invalidated the rule on equal protection grounds.39 At oral argument, however, plaintiff’s LSO attorney sought a statutory ruling. ‘[I]f the decision goes off as the lower court’s did, then very little will have been accomplished. Even if we win in Alabama, HEW will not stop similar practices in other states [where man-in-the-house rules had no such discriminatory purpose or effect].’40 A statutory holding, ‘would give us all we wanted,’41 providing ‘a way in which the narrowest of rulings would have the broadest of implications. … “[G]ive us,”’42 counsel asked the Court speaking for the NWRO rank-and-file, “a decision interpreting the Social Security Act as having rejected the concept of a worthy and an unworthy poor”’.43 And the Court did so, giving welfare rights attorneys a reading of the Act that would shape AFDC case law for the next two decades.44 In the face of legislative history that ran almost entirely to the contrary, a unanimous Supreme Court concluded that in 1935 Congress had intended that all ‘needy, dependent children’ would be entitled to AFDC benefits, and that states and localities could not enforce their own narrower definitions of eligible parents. Thus, Alabama, in dispersing AFDC, could not decide that Mrs. Smith’s occasional visitor and lover (a Mr Williams with nine children of his own) was a ‘substitute father’ and breadwinner whose visits to Mrs Smith disqualified her and her children from the federal entitlement.45 Chief Justice Warren put aside a wealth of legislative history suggesting that Congress intended pre- cisely to allow states to apply their own standards of ‘moral character’ and ‘suitability’ (acqui- escing, as we saw, to the southern Democrats’ insistence on local control over ‘domestic affairs’ of race, caste, and the social and economic authority of local white elites). This history might have been relevant at one time, Warren noted, because the ‘social context’ in 1935 was one in which the distinction between the ‘worthy’ poor and the ‘undeserving’ was generally accept- ed.46 Now both society and Congress took a different view, ‘more sophisticated and enlight- ened than the “worthy-person” concept of earlier times.’47 The evidence that the Congresses that enacted the various post-1935 amendments to AFDC shared the Warren Court’s enlight- ened perspective was scant at best.48 Nonetheless, the Chief Justice proceeded to read the pre- amble and statement of purpose of the 1935 Act itself to mean that AFDC ‘was designed to meet a need unmet by programs providing employment for breadwinners.’49 Thus, ‘at the same time that it intended to provide programs for the economic security and protection of all children . . . [Congress surely would not have allowed the states] arbitrarily to 39 Smith v King 277 F Supp 31 41 (MD Ala 1967). 40 M Garbus Ready for the Defense (1971) 194. 41 Idem. 42 Idem at 194-95. 43 Idem (internal quotations omitted). 44 See King 392 US 309. 45 Idem at 328-30. 46 Idem at 320, 324-35. 47 Idem at 324-25. 48 The year before, in 1967, Congress had enacted amendments to AFDC that penalized states if they failed to reduce the number of illegitimate children on AFDC. Senator Robert Kennedy complained that ‘the man- in-the-house rule emerges from the conference strengthened rather than weakened’ and joined with other liberals in an unsuccessful attempt to kill the conference report. Melnick (note 22 above) at 87 (quoting 113 Cong Rec 36785 (Dec 14 1967)) (internal quotations omitted). 49 King v Smith 392 US at 328. leave one class of destitute children entirely without meaningful protection… Such an interpre- tation of congressional intent would be most unreasonable, and we decline to adopt it.’50 Relying on King v Smith,51 LSO attorneys went on to challenge a wide variety of state prac- tices. Most northern states had their own, less draconian man-in-the-house rules, like New York’s, which did not disqualify the family, but put some financial burden on the man in- volved.52 The lower courts took a hard line against all such practices, and the Supreme Court upheld them, enshrining a principle of ‘actual availability.’53 Thus, the much-resented man-in- the-house rule fell by the wayside, its defeat a victory for the welfare rights movement’s vision of woman’s autonomy. Other forms of presumed income also were successfully challenged, and the upshot was that courts indirectly increased family’s benefits.54 In the process of expanding their attack on man-in-the-house and other attributed income rules, the courts strengthened the general presumption against all types of state-imposed restrictions. Few facets of AFDC policy escaped scrutiny in the lower courts. State laws penalizing recipients for fraud; laws and regulations denying benefits to aliens; rules on verification procedure, foster care, and emergency assistance were all struck down.55 During the first thirty years of AFDC’s existence, there had been but one reported federal case interpreting the statute. Then, between 1968 and 1975, the years Frank Michelman wrote his first seminal pieces on welfare rights, the Supreme Court decided eighteen AFDC cases, and the lower federal courts decided hundreds more.56 Chiefly through statutory construction, the federal judiciary had gone a great distance toward transforming a grant-in-aid to the states into a no-strings, no-stigma, national right to welfare. But statutory construction could go only so far. It could not establish a decent social minimum as a floor on welfare benefits, or even prevent the states from diminishing payments as they expanded coverage under judicial nudging.57 And it could not challenge the exclusions inscribed in the statute’s categorical system, forcing Congress to change the system into one embracing all of the nation’s poor. If courts were to force these changes, it would be through constitutional adjudication. At first, LSO relied heavily on constitutional challenges. Residency requirements, as we’ve noted, carried forward a centuries-old tradition of localities warning out wayfaring paupers. Nine out of eleven lower courts agreed with welfare rights groups and the LSO that these requirements trenched on the welfare recipient’s right to travel; to be a member of the nation- al community had always included the right freely to travel among the states.58 In Shapiro v Thompson, the Supreme Court agreed that the states’ residency requirements unconstitutional- ly burdened poor Americans’ enjoyment of that right.59 More than that, Justice Brennan, writ- Frank Michelman on Social Rights 81 50 Idem at 330. 51 392 US 309 (1968). 52 Van Lare v Hurley 421 US 338 339-42 (1975). 53 Melnick (note 22 above) at 88-89; Lewis v Martin 397 US 552 (1970). 54 Melnick (note 22 above) at 89. 55 See eg Holley v Lavine 553 F2d 845 851 (2d Cir 1977) (rules excluding aliens); Maryland v Mathews 415 F Supp 1206 (DDC 1976) (verification procedures); Owens v Roberts 377 F Supp 45 (MD Fla 1974); JA v Riti 377 F Supp 1046 (DFNJ 1974) (rules penalizing fraud); Cooper v Laupheimer 316 F Supp 264 (ED Pa 1970) (rules on emergency assistance). 56 See generally Lawrence (note 37 above). 57 Rosado v Wyman 397 US 397 416-17 (1970). 58 Forbath ‘Constitutional Welfare Rights’ (note 7 above) at 1862. 59 394 US 618 629-31 (1969). On the lower court litigation and rulings against residency requirements, see FS Bloch ‘Cooperative Federalism and the Role of Litigation in the Development of Federal AFDC Eligibility Policy’ (1979) Wis LR 1 at 8-12. 8 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E ing for the Court, seemed to suggest (Justice Harlan, in dissent, called it a ‘cryptic suggestion’60) that strict scrutiny, applying the compelling state interest test to the residency requirement, might be justified for another reason not the right to travel, but the fact that welfare affects ‘the ability of the families to obtain the very means to subsist.’61 (B) GOLDBERG V KELLY, THE ‘NEW PROPERTY,’ AND THE HARD QUESTIONS Eight lower courts heard LSO challenges to states’ summary termination practices, and six held that the due process clause required pre-termination hearings.62 In 1970, with its decision in Goldberg v Kelly,63 the Supreme Court upheld the majority view.64 Declaring that welfare benefits were ‘a matter of statutory entitlement … [whose] termina- tion involves state action that adjudicates important rights,’65 Goldberg encapsulated the pre- vious five years of federal litigation and decisional law. By recognizing private rights of action, stripping broad swathes of discretionary power from local officials, and eliminating non-need based eligibility criteria, this new body of law had made welfare benefits into just such rights. The Court seemed to go further, stating more fully and forcefully than ever before the premis- es behind the ‘more sophisticated and enlightened’ view of welfare it had evoked (and attrib- uted to Congress) in King.66 In a footnote supporting its assertion that welfare benefits were ‘a matter of statutory entitlement,’ the Court observed, ‘it may be realistic today to regard wel- fare entitlements as more like ‘property’ than a ‘gratuity.’ Much of the existing wealth in this country takes the form of rights that do not fall within traditional common-law concepts of property. It has been aptly noted that ‘[s]ociety today is built around entitlement… . Many of the most important of these entitlements now flow from government: subsidies to farmers and businessmen … [and] social security pensions for individuals. Such sources of security, whether private or public, are no longer regarded as luxuries or gratuities; to the recipients they are essentials, fully deserved, and in no sense a form of charity. It is only the poor whose entitle- ments, although recognized by public policy, have not been effectively enforced.’67 The long quotation was from Charles Reich, whose two enormously influential articles on the ‘new property’ were published in Yale Law Journal in 1964 and 1965.68 It is an argument about the status of welfare in an era in which ‘government largess’ takes myriad forms and con- stitutes so much of individual and corporate wealth. In Reich’s account, the welfare recipient belonged to a whole social order of Americans ‘liv[ing] on government largess.’69 ‘Social insur- ance substitutes for savings[, and] a government contract replaces a businessman’s customers and goodwill,’70 while in between the new pauper and pensioner and the new businessmen 60 Shapiro v Thompson 394 US at 661 (Harlan J dissenting). 61 Idem at 627 (majority). 62 Forbath ‘Constitutional Welfare Rights’ (note 7 above) at 1863. 63 397 US 254 (1970). 64 See Bloch (note 59 above). 65 397 US at 262. 66 392 US at 324-25. 67 Goldberg 397 US at 262 fn 8 (quoting CA Reich ‘Individual Rights and Social Welfare: The Emerging Legal Issues’ (1965) 74 Yale LJ 1245 at 1255). 68 See CA Reich ‘Individual Rights and Social Welfare: The Emerging Legal Issues’ (1965) 74 Yale LJ 1245 [hereinafter Reich ‘Individual Rights and Social Welfare’]; CA Reich ‘The “New Property’’ ’ (1964) 73 Yale LJ 733 [hereinafter Reich ‘New Property’]. 69 Reich ‘New Property’ (note 68 above) at 733. 70 Idem. stood petty entrepreneurs and tradesmen, the cab driver dependent on his medallion, the tav- ern keeper and the hunting guide whose livelihoods hinged on their licenses.71 In Reich’s anx- ious and nostalgic liberal narrative of American life, political and cultural antagonists, the cab driver or tradesman and the welfare mother, the factory owner and the union worker, were unit- ed by their common vulnerability to the state.72 In fact, precious few of Reich’s disparate forms of ‘new property’ were new.73 But the assimilation of pauper to tradesman and franchise-hold- er, the equation of welfare benefits with professional licenses and government contracts, was dramatically new, and this did the important discursive and doctrinal work. The ‘new proper- ty’ unlike the old was dispensed by the state in ‘the form of rights or status rather than of tan- gible goods.’74 How, then, Reich asked, can the new property fulfill the social function of the old property? How can it serve as an institution that secures the individual a measure of inde- pendence from state domination, when it is itself dispensed by the state?75 The question sound- ed in classical liberalism, and so did the answer. If government subsidies, contracts, pensions, and benefits were to serve as a basis for private autonomy and dignified existence, fulfilling the social function of property, then these various forms of largess must enjoy the same legal pro- tections as traditional common law forms of property. In particular, the new property, like the old, must be protected against arbitrary deprivations and invasions by the state. What the state gave, the state could not take away, at least not without due process. And, in fact, Reich observed, due process case law already had begun in the 1950s to estab- lish that the state could not take away such government-granted goods as an occupational license without ‘notice and a hearing.’76 Where the ‘freedom to earn a living’ was implicated, courts recog- nized that procedural due process’s protections of property applied. But welfare too involved liveli- hood; like traditional livelihoods, it had the potential to provide ‘a secure minimum basis for indi- vidual well-being and dignity,’77 but only if the legal order recognized it too as a form of property. For all its resonance, Reich’s argument left many questions dangling, and so did Goldberg. First was the question of distributive justice. Conceding that welfare benefits, if recognized as secure legal entitlements, could perform the ‘social functions’ Reich and the Court claimed for them, why were the poor entitled to them? On what distributive premise did they rest? On the face of it, wel- fare was not a moral equivalent to a professional license or a pension right in a union contract or even to government-based, but partly contributory, social insurance. Effort and exchange were the ordinary normative bases in liberal legal culture for such ‘property’ claims. What was the norma- tive argument that made welfare a cognate right, when on the face of it, welfare differed from the others by distributing goods with neither effort nor exchange to underpin the result? Second was the question of whether the legal/constitutional order’s recognition of welfare as a right had only formal and procedural bite. If the social function of welfare as property was to pro- vide ‘a secure minimum basis for individual well-being and dignity,’ then did the entitlement not entail a measure of substantive constitutional protection—say, against lawmakers’ decision to repeal the entitlement or to diminish it below the minimum?78 Or was that kind of recognition of the property-like aspect of welfare strictly a matter of public policy for legislatures to determine? Frank Michelman on Social Rights 83 71 See idem at 758-59. 72 Agency discretion wielded ‘life and death’ power over the livelihoods of one and all. See idem at 758. 73 See WJ Novak The People’s Welfare: Law and Regulation in Nineteenth-Century America (1996). 74 See Reich ‘New Property’ (note 68 above) at 738. 75 See idem. 76 Idem at 741. 77 Idem at 786. 78 Idem. 8 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E For Reich the right to welfare seemed to rest on the involuntary nature of individual poverty. ‘Today,’ he wrote in the full text of the passage from which the Goldberg Court quoted: we see poverty as the consequence of large impersonal forces in a complex industri- al society … [Past eras saw poverty as flowing from individual ‘idleness’ and other moral failings.] It is closer to the truth to say that the poor are affirmative contribu- tors to today’s society, for we are so organized as virtually to compel this sacrifice by a segment of the population. Since the enactment of the Social Security Act, we have recognized that they have a right – not a mere privilege – to a minimal share in the commonwealth.79 As an assertion about the commitments inscribed in the nation’s statutes, this is bunk.80 As moral reasoning, it also is somewhat odd. We may view compelled sacrifices as affirmative con- tributions to the commonwealth, but these tend to involve some measure of individual exertion say, the sacrifices endured as a conscript in a national army. What Reich describes here is more like a casualty loss from the accident of poverty or rather the accidental loss of a livelihood because American society is ‘so organized as virtually to compel’ one’s exclusion from the labor market. This would point toward welfare as a kind of just compensation. Of course, the compensation clause is not where the Court looked for constitutional footing. ‘From its founding the Nation’s basic commitment has been to foster the dignity and well-being of all persons within its borders. We have come to recognize that forces not within the control of the poor contribute to their poverty,’81 the Court observed, citing and paraphrasing Reich. Welfare, by meeting the basic demands of subsistence, can help bring within the reach of the poor the same opportunities that are available to others to participate meaningfully in the life of the community … . Public assistance, then, is not mere charity, but a means to ‘promote the general Welfare, and secure the Blessings of Liberty to ourselves and our Posterity.’82 So, the Court did not follow Reich in his blunt assertion that welfare was the poor person’s just desert as a conscript in the reserve army of the unemployed. It did suggest that because supra-individual, social forces ‘contribute’ to a person’s poverty, welfare should be dignifying and not degrading. Indeed, it implied that assuring that the material bases of ‘well-being’ were available in a dignifying manner stood as a fundamental or ‘founding’ national ‘commitment.’ Reich’s bleak quid pro quo rubbed abrasively against the ideal of equal opportunity. That ideal signified bringing the nation’s poor into a shared world of work and opportunity, not compen- sating them for permanent exclusion from it. So, the Court cast welfare not as compensation for the jobless poor’s involuntary ‘contribution’ to the economy, but as a means of bringing within their reach ‘opportunities … to participate … in the life of the community.’ Presumably, this meant that without means of subsistence, the poor could not begin to attain education and decent work or to participate in civic life. Participating in these spheres not welfare as such is the social basis of equal citizenship, which is why welfare was more the fruit of the New Deal’s 79 Reich ‘Individual Rights and Social Welfare’ (note 68 above) at 1255. 80 In point of fact, the Social Security Act recognized no such right; it provided time-limited unemployment insurance and old-age pensions to those who contributed, mothers’ pensions (ADC), and public assistance for the blind and the elderly poor—those who could not presently or could no longer be expected to work, and nothing at all for the ‘idle poor.’ See Forbath ‘Constitutional Welfare Rights’ (note 7 above) at 68-81. 81 Goldberg 397 US at 264-65. 82 Idem at 265 (quoting US Constitution preamble). failure to enact social citizenship than its fulfillment. But here, in a case involving the children and grandchildren of the very Americans the New Deal had excluded, the Court was casting welfare provision, in the words of the Preamble, as a step toward including all Americans in a common framework of ‘Liberty’ and ‘the general welfare.’ With these striking references to the Constitution, the Court seemed to be signaling a will- ingness to consider whether some constitutional provision might grant a right to welfare for those confronting what the Court called ‘brutal need.’83 As we’ve seen, this was the push of the Court’s remarkable statutory construction cases that welfare was an individual entitlement and need the only legitimate touchstone of exclusion from it. The Court’s reference to ‘the Blessings of Liberty’ suggested, in strong echoes of Roosevelt’s ‘second Bill of Rights,’ that a measure of economic security was indispensable to freedom and citizenship.84 Even more clearly, the Court spurned the notion that welfare was simply a humanitarian measure; rather, it was a means of bringing ‘within the reach of the poor … opportunities … to participate meaningfully in the life of the community.’85 Welfare, then, was being cast as a necessary, though not a sufficient, basis of equal citizenship, a step toward including all Americans in a common framework of ‘Liberty,’ a matter of obvious constitutional significance. Thus, the Court seemed to be verging on judicial recognition of something very much like rights to minimum welfare, education, and other forms of social provision, when the Republican victory in the 1968 presidential election deprived the Court’s liberals of the votes they needed to carry the process forward. In 1969, President Nixon appointed Warren Burger; in 1970, Harry Blackmun, whose first years on the Court saw him aligned with the new Chief; in 1972, Nixon appointed Lewis Powell and William Rehnquist. Who can doubt that four Humphrey appointments, instead of four Nixon appointments, would have made the Dandridge v Williams86 and San Antonio Independent School District v Rodriguez87 dissents into majority opinions? In Dandridge, the lower court had built on Goldberg and the other welfare rights precedents to strike down Maryland’s dollar maximum (of $250 per month) on welfare grants to poor families. Plaintiffs claimed that the maximum discriminated against poor children in large fam- ilies, and the court agreed, applying heightened scrutiny to the measure because it affected the constitutionally important interest in welfare, and concluding that the law ‘cut[] too broad a swath on an indiscriminate basis.’88 Under the new Chief Justice’s leadership, the Supreme Court reversed, announcing that no longer would the Court attend to the details of welfare pro- grams, even if they appeared discriminatory or made harsh distinctions among people equally in need. Acknowledging that ‘administration of public welfare assistance … involves the most basic economic needs of impoverished human beings,’89 the Court declared that ‘the dramati- cally real factual difference between [welfare regulation and regulation of business or industry provided] no basis for applying a different constitutional standard.’90 Frank Michelman on Social Rights 85 83 Idem at 261 (quoting Kelly v Wyman 294 F Supp 893 900 (SDFNY 1968) (quoting Student Author ‘Withdrawal of Public Welfare: The Right to a Prior Hearing’(1967) 76 Yale LJ 1234 at 1234, 1244)) (inter- nal quotations omitted). 84 Goldberg v Kelly 397 US at 265. 85 Idem. 86 397 US 471 (1970). 87 411 US 1 (1973). 88 Dandridge v Williams 397 US at 484 (quoting Williams v Dandridge 297 F Supp 450 469 (D Md 1968)) (internal quotations omitted). 89 Idem at 485. 90 Idem. 8 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E In dissent, Justice Marshall assailed ‘the Court’s emasculation of the Equal Protection Clause as a constitutional principle applicable to the area of social welfare administration.’91 Marshall approvingly invoked the arguments of Michelman and others on behalf of a substantive right to welfare, as well as Article 25 of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights,92 which confers just such a right. Thus, he signaled the dissenters’ inclination to read the Constitution as conferring something like a right to livelihood. On a Humphrey, rather than a Nixon, Court, the trajectory of constitutional doctrine after Dandridge most likely would have been in the direction of ever more exigent signals that Congress and the States must make up shortfalls between statutory offerings and the real world of ‘brutal need’ and include the statutorily excluded. (C) MICHELMAN ON THE HARD QUESTIONS: ‘MINIMUM PROTECTION,’ ‘JUST WANTS,’ AND ‘BASIC NEEDS’ Dandridge, however, lay in the future as Frank Michelman set to work on the unfinished nor- mative underpinnings of constitutional welfare rights. The federal courts had labored mightily in statutory AFDC cases to make need the sole criterion for eligibility. Justice Brennan, in Shapiro, remember, even had intimated that need of families for the very means of subsistence might become a member of the new constitutional family of fundamental interests, and there- by subject classifications in and exclusions from welfare statutes to strict scrutiny.93 But need had never stood on the same plane as effort or exchange in the distributive norms of common law or constitutional doctrine. Need needed an argument that sounded in distributive justice. Charles Reich’s articles did not provide one.94 Reich urged courts to attack official arbitrari- ness and discretion, and the insecurity and indignities they bred. He offered a sociological rationale for treating statutory welfare benefits as rights, but no moral or constitutional argu- ment why courts were obliged to provide for the needy whom lawmakers had left out, or to remedy the shortfalls between statutory offerings and actual need. From the point of view of a legal scholar who sympathized with the welfare rights movement, the need-based right still needed arguments that extended beyond procedural to distributive justice and addressed the right’s substantive reach and bounds. Frank Michelman set out in search of such arguments. He reported on his progress in two pioneering articles, the 1969 Harvard Foreword, ‘On Protecting the Poor through the Fourteenth Amendment,’95 and his 1973 ‘In Pursuit of Constitutional Welfare Rights: One View of Rawls’ Theory of Justice.’96 ‘Protecting the Poor’ was an effort to nudge doctrine and doctrinal scholarship toward a theory of judicially enforceable constitutional welfare rights. ‘In Pursuit of Constitutional Welfare Rights’ was a reading of John Rawls’s epoch-making book,97 examining how Rawls’s theory bore on the idea of justiciable welfare rights, and how such an examination, in turn, might illuminate Rawls’s theory. 91 Idem at 508 (Marshall & Brennan dissenting). 92 Idem at 521 fn 14. 93 See 394 US at 638. 94 The text oversimplifies. Reich, as we saw, did gesture toward a justificatory argument based on compen- sation: welfare was just compensation for society’s more or less conscious choice of a political economy that offered too few decently paid jobs to go around. 95 Michelman (note 13 above). 96 FI Michelman ‘In Pursuit of “Constitutional Welfare Rights”: One View of Rawls’ Theory of Justice’ (1973) 121 U Pa LR 962. 97 See Rawls (note 8 above). What, asked Michelman, is ‘the role of courts … [in] the great War’98 on poverty? He answered with a reading of a handful of recent equal protection decisions Shapiro, which had been decided in the 1968 Term, Harper v Virginia State Board of Elections,99 Douglas v California,100 and a few of their kin. Michelman dubbed these cases the Court’s ‘contribution to the great War.’101 Shapiro, Harper, and Douglas all could be read as resting, partly, on a notion of wealth discrimi- nation.102 Many lower courts103 and liberal commentators wishfully read them as signs that the Court might bring the nation’s poor into the ‘inner circle’ of judicially protected classes.104 For his part, Michelman read the decisions differently. The Court, he agreed, was embarking on ‘the elaboration of constitutional rights pertaining to the status of being poor,’105 and it had clothed the decisions presaging these rights in the ‘verbiage of inequality and discrimination.’106 But the ‘inchoate theories of social justice … at the roots’107 of these cases was ill expressed in the language of ‘equality or evenhandedness.’108 Applying strict scrutiny to laws that fall unequally on the nation’s poor would sweep too broadly; such government action is everywhere. Nor does equality offer a plausible benchmark for answering the question how much protection is ‘enough.’ ‘”As much as” seems to provide just the certainty of measure which “enough of” so sorely lacks.’109 But Frank Michelman on Social Rights 87 98 See Michelman (note 13 above) at 8-9. 99 383 US 663 (1966) (holding that state may not condition franchise on payment of tax or fee). 100 372 US 353 (1963) (holding that state must provide counsel to criminal accused on first appeal as of right, irrespective of court’s assessment of probable merits). 101 See Michelman (note 13 above) at 9. 102 Harper held that statutes discriminating on the basis of wealth were, like those discriminating based on race, ‘traditionally disfavored’ 383 US at 668. Douglas spoke of ‘that equality demanded by the Fourteenth Amendment where the rich man … enjoys the benefit of counsel’s [assistance] … while the indi- gent … is forced to shift for himself’: 372 US at 358. The Court noted that ‘the evil [in such a situation] is … discrimination against the indigent,’ idem at 355, and that ‘an unconstitutional line has been drawn between rich and poor.’ Id at 357. In his Shapiro dissent, Justice Harlan lamented the majority’s ‘cryptic suggestion’ that welfare constituted a fundamental interest giving rise to the strict scrutiny/compelling state interest test the Court’s emergent equal protection doctrine had begun to extend from suspect racial classi- fications to other invidious discriminations and fundamental constitutional interests nowhere evident in the constitutional text: 394 US at 661 (Harlan J dissenting). 103 Thus, the same year as Michelman’s ‘Protecting the Poor,’ a three-judge district court in New York enjoined a recent change in the state’s welfare regulations, which reduced public assistance payments in counties sur- rounding New York City to levels below those paid to city residents, when they had previously been grouped together. Rothstein v Wyman 303 F Supp 339 (SD FNY 1969). Applying strict scrutiny to the new classification scheme, the district court wrote, ‘Receipt of welfare benefits may not at the present time constitute the exercise of a constitutional right’; nonetheless, the court deemed controlling the teaching of Harper and Shapiro, that classifications creating ‘inequalities affecting the exercise of fundamental or crit- ical personal rights’ must be scrutinized under ‘a more stringent standard’: idem at 346. As in Harper and Shapiro, so here the court found a conjunction of a ‘fundamental right’ and a ‘disadvantaged minority’— only here the right was welfare and the minority the poor. While welfare was only an incipient constitu- tional right, an emergent fundamental interest, Shapiro still seemed to the Rothstein court to mark the Supreme Court’s acknowledgment that ‘[a]ccess to [the] bare necessities of life’ was as ‘fundamental’ as vot- ing. See idem at 346-48. And Douglas marked a dawning recognition of the poor as a protected minority. 104 See JE Coons et al ‘Educational Opportunity: A Workable Constitutional Test for State Financial Structures’ (1969) 57 Cal LR 305 at 365; See generally AJ Goldberg ‘Equality and Governmental Action’ (1964) 39 FNY U LR 205; LG Sager ‘Tight Little Islands: Exclusionary Zoning, Equal Protection, and the Indigent’ (1969) 21 Stan LR 767. 105 See Michelman (note 13 above) at 16. 106 Idem. 107 Idem at 10. 108 Idem. 109 Idem at 18. 8 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E would a court be comfortable explaining ‘why X is entitled to, say, [as much legal assistance on his appeal as] Y in fact has rather than what justice requires?’110 If equal protection, as applied to the plight of poverty, swept too broadly, it also stopped short of the mark, because equal protection implies ‘a “state action” qualification upon government’s duties to relieve against hazards of pover- ty.’111 Yet, it was ‘less easy to be reconciled to the “state action” notion when alleviation of cer- tain, specially poignant hardships or crushing disadvantages is thought to be the object… . [Then,] the government’s noninvolvement … may come not as relief but as reproach.’112 Thus, while inequality and discrimination were the doctrinal notions near at hand, they were misleading. The upsetting feature in the equal protection cases involving poverty was not some odious discrimination that might accompany a poor person’s deprivation of a good he couldn’t afford; what was disturbing was the deprivation itself. So, Michelman sought to use the cases as data points from which to infer the outlines of a constitutional universe of ‘just wants’ or ‘basic needs.’ Not equal protection, he insisted, but ‘minimum protection’ was the heart of the matter.113 Focusing on specific deprivations of basic needs was ‘a much more manageable task’114 for courts. Michelman strapped himself to the mast of moderation, and vowed to keep ‘resolutely deaf to [the Court’s] superfluous [equality] rhetoric.’115 His was a more modest picture of the courts’ part in ending poverty: not ‘railing against tides of economic inequality which they [can’t stem], but … busy with the critically important task of charting some islands of haven from eco- nomic disaster in the ocean of (what continues to be known as) free enterprise.’116 After Dandridge and Rodriguez, it became fairly clear that most of the Justices on the Burger Court would not compel states or Congress to make up any shortfall between statutory offerings and the real world of ‘brutal need,’ nor etch out a constitutional universe of just wants, nor subject state laws or practices that fell heavily or arbitrarily on the poor to any exacting constitutional stan- dard. Not unless there were some other, more familiar constitutional value entwined in the case: the fairness of the criminal process, ending the South’s disenfranchisement of blacks and poor whites, vindicating the citizen’s right to travel among the states of the Union free from discrimination. Indeed, the idea that ‘lawyers in criminal courts are necessities, not luxuries’117 harked back to the 1930s and Powell v Alabama;118 it spoke to the Court’s special solicitude for the integri- ty of the judicial process and its sensitivity toward the charge that ‘the rich man can require the court to listen to argument of counsel before deciding on the merits, but a poor man cannot.’119 Harper, striking down Virginia’s poll tax, seems likely to have been akin to Powell in most Justices’ minds, completing the dismantling of Jim Crow, rather than identifying the first ‘islands of [economic] haven’120 on a constitutional map of basic needs and just wants. What is important for us about ‘Protecting the Poor,’ however, is not its failed prophecy about doctrinal developments, which, after all, may merely have been the upshot of Nixon’s 110 Michelman (note 13 above) at 18. 111 Idem at 11. 112 Idem. 113 Idem at 13-14. 114 Idem at 8. 115 Michelman (note 13 above) at 33. 116 Idem. 117 Gideon v Wainwright 372 US 335 344 (1963) (holding that indigent felony defendants entitled to state- funded trial counsel under the Sixth Amendment). 118 287 US 45 (1932) (holding that indigent defendant in capital case entitled to state-financed counsel under the Sixth Amendment). 119 Douglas 372 US at 357. 120 Michelman (note 13 above) at 33. razor-thin victory in the 1968 election. What matters here is the Foreword’s optimism about the open-ended quality of those developments and its identification of courts and author with the ‘great War’ on poverty. As we noted, ‘Protecting the Poor’ was written with ‘funds provided by’ the command center of that ‘War’ and while Michelman was associated with Harvard’s LSO back-up center.121 The Harvard Center litigated special education and school desegregation cases; like other LSO offices, its occupants saw themselves battling against the intertwined evils of racism and poverty, training scores of LSO attorneys and working with community organi- zations.122 Unlike other back-up centers, like Columbia’s, it lacked a strong ‘movement’ tilt, and had nothing quite like Columbia’s close ties with the NWRO.123 Intellectually, however, Michelman joined the NWRO and the attorneys and policy mavens surrounding it in their sharp break with inherited rights discourse. In contrast with the NWRO, ‘Protecting the Poor’ and ‘In Pursuit of Constitutional Welfare Rights’ do not defend a guaran- teed income but instead a bundle of ‘insurance rights’ (to food, shelter, health care, education). But in common with the NWRO, Michelman breaks the link with work. His constitutional wel- fare rights are unconditional. Thus, with the NWRO, Michelman rejects the centuries-old dis- tinctions between ‘worthy’ and ‘unworthy’ candidates for public provision. There are no dis- tinctions here between the disabled and able-bodied, the ill-fated and blameworthy, the wid- owed and promiscuous, the earnest job-seeker and the shiftless and idle.124 Instead, Michelman means to summon forth a theory of distributive justice that is insistently unsatisfied by a polit- ical economy affording everyone a ‘fair opportunity’ through ‘full employment,’ ‘income trans- fers,’ and the like125 to provide for everyone’s basic needs or just wants. ‘Protecting the Poor’ requires ‘more’; it requires basic needs or just wants ‘will be met when and as felt, [regardless of] … effort, thrift, or foresight.’126 Michelman does not dispute that justice requires the kind of political economy that enables everyone to make a decent living through decent work. At one point, he even notes that a par- ticipant in a Rawlsian assembly might well seek in addition, and perhaps even prior to, insur- ance rights assurance of some of social citizenship’s mainstays in the form of full employment, income supplements, and the like.127 But apart from this passing observation, work in all its forms waged and unwaged, dignifying and demeaning, decently rewarded and socially valued and not does not figure at all in Michelman’s account of the constitutional dimensions of the ‘great War’ on poverty.128 In this, of course, Michelman departs from the social citizenship tra- Frank Michelman on Social Rights 89 121 Idem at 7 fn *. 122 See generally MW Edelman Lanterns: A Memoir of Mentors (1999). Edelman was a director of the Harvard Center on Law and Education. 123 See Forbath ‘Constitutional Welfare Rights’ (note 7 above) at 1855-59. 124 Michelman welcomes the challenge to answer the ‘compelling … objection to welfare rights, that such rights signify redistribution from the prudent and industrious to those who have culpably failed to grasp oppor- tunities to provide for their own security’: Michelman (note 96 above) at 969. 125 See Michelman (note 13 above) at 14 fn 18. 126 Idem at 14. 127 Idem at 15 fn 21. 128 One might think that such social citizenship principles as a right to work are absent from Michelman’s con- stitutional theorizing, because they lie beyond anything courts could hope to contribute to the anti-poverty campaign. But it seems fair to say that for the Michelman of these two essays, ‘minimum protection’ consti- tutes the full reach of the Constitution’s—and not merely the constitutional courts’ ’protection of the poor.’ No Constitution seen from the vantage point of civil society or of Congress would contain any different rights or equality norms. As we’ll see, infra text accompanying notes 172-78, Michelman does address constitutional advocacy in political fora, and he casts the social minimum for constituting equal citizenship in the same mold. ‘Insurance rights’ remain the constitutional ticket, whether in Congress or in the courts. 9 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E dition I have reconstructed and chronicled elsewhere.129 It sought to find or include these norms in the Constitution—to serve, in much the same terms that Michelman applies to welfare rights, as touchstones for ‘convincing advocacy’ and ‘foothold[s] for challenging legislative judg- ments’130 that fell short of assuring decent work opportunities and decent livelihoods for all.131 This lacuna results in an argument for welfare rights that assigns those rights social work they cannot do; they cannot secure the social bases of self-respect and mutual respect in American life. Or so I will suggest. But I will do so in the context of a critical reading of Michelman’s reading of Rawls, to which we must turn. IV A Critical Reading of Michelman on Rawls and Welfare Rights (A) THE DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE AND CONSTITUTIONAL POLITICAL ECONOMY What was afoot in the courts shaped the way Michelman approached Rawls’s A Theory of Justice. When Michelman turned in earnest to Rawls, he did so with a mind to asking [h]ow … the book [bore] upon the work of legal investigators concerned or curious about recognition, through legal processes, of claimed affirmative rights (let us call them “welfare rights”) to education, shelter, subsistence, health care and the like, or to the money these things cost.132 The answer was a vexed one. Michelman rested welfare rights on a distributive principle of ‘minimum protection’ or ‘just wants’; Rawls offered something different. The chief basis for welfare rights or for ‘the money these things cost’ in A Theory of Justice was Rawls’s difference principle. The difference principle, you’ll recall, states that institutionalized inequalities must be justified by dint of being in the interests of the least advantaged.133 Inequalities that do not redound to the benefit of those at the bottom are illegitimate. For Rawls, this principle is not cashed out through income standards or transfer payments alone; it must imbue the general ‘organization of the econ- omy,’ and the distribution of wealth, power, and authority as well as income.134 Because his focus rests on welfare, however, Michelman reads the difference principle with an eye to income. ‘Even apart from the quest for justiciability,’135 he writes (and we will return to that quest), ‘the differ- ence principle is unsatisfactory’;136 for Rawls seems interested simply in maximizing the income 129 See Forbath ‘Caste, Class, and Equal Citizenship’ (note 7 above). 130 Michelman (note 96 above) at 1003. 131 Idem at 1002-03. Compare Michelman’s language about welfare rights arguments in political fora to the statements of New Dealers, which I quote in some detail, in ‘Caste, Class, and Equal Citizenship’ (note 7 above) suggesting that constitutional social and economic rights should serve as standards for the polity to judge ‘the acts of legislatures and executives.’ 132 Michelman (note 96 above) at 962. 133 See Rawls (note 8 above) at 100-01; J Rawls Political Liberalism (1996) 283. Michelman explicates and crit- icizes the difference principle in ‘In Pursuit of ‘Constitutional Welfare Rights’,’ (note 96 above) at 976-88. 134 See Rawls (note 8 above) at 7-11, 54. 135 Michelman (note 96 above) at 982. 136 Idem. of those at the bottom, irrespective of whether that income is adequate to meeting basic needs,137 or whether it substantially exceeds that level.138 Moreover, Michelman finds it difficult to feed the ‘primary good of self-respect’139 into the machinery of the difference principle, because the good of self-respect ‘does not seem to fit the difference principle’s “more is better” attitude.’140 Yet, from the point of view of liberal constitutional theory, the centrality of self-respect and equal respect in Rawls’s theory are an important part of his appeal. Michelman does find some support for a just wants/insurance rights approach to welfare elsewhere in Rawls’s theory. While the difference principle is uncongenial, it is possible that Rawls’s equal liberty principle or his principle of fair equality of opportunity, or even ‘justice as fairness’ as a whole implies a bundle of ‘insurance rights’ such as Michelman is champi- oning.141 Mainly, however, Michelman focuses on explicating and assessing the difference prin- ciple as a source of welfare rights. Unlike the ‘more is better’ attitude of Rawls’s difference principle, Michelman’s ‘just wants’ theory provides a touchstone for determining the metes and bounds of welfare provision that seems directly tied to equal respect.142 Beyond the point at which welfare provides a decent minimum of social goods, it seems wiser to allow considerations of economic incentives and market efficiency to hold sway. As a rational actor behind Rawls’s ‘veil of ignorance,’ one might well prefer assurance that one’s ‘just wants’ be satisfied, and for the rest one might prefer to wager that one’s individual capacities were at least middling as the market measures things and choose against the ‘more is better’ attitude of the difference principle. Certainly, Michelman makes a valuable point about the vulnerability of the difference prin- ciple from the point of view of calibrating welfare rights or a minimum income. However, we risk being misled if we look at the difference principle only from this perspective. From it, we might surmise that what separates Rawls’s views about social and economic rights from Michelman’s is simply a quarrel over what form of income redistribution to enshrine in the Constitution minimum income pegged to the difference principle, or minimum welfare rights pegged to just wants. In fact, neither of these alternatives captures Rawls’s view of how the principles of justice, including the difference principle, bear on constitutional political econo- Frank Michelman on Social Rights 91 137 ‘A precept for the distribution of material social goods,’ writes Michelman ‘which ignores claims regarding basic needs as such, and is sensitive only to claims regarding money income, will for many of us Seem incomplete and thus not fully in harmony with our “considered judgments”’. 138 Michelman states: ‘Income-transfer activity is simply to be intensified just up to the point where any fur- ther intensification lowers total output so much that the bottom’s absolute income begins to fall even as its relative share of total consumer satisfaction continues to rise. Under the difference principle, that is all there is to it. There can be no implicit insurance-rights package because there is no concern for what the bottom spends (or is able to spend) its income own: Income is income a primary, an elemental, social good, of which the bottom simply wants and is entitled to as much as it can get’: idem at 981. 139 Idem at 983. 140 Michelman (note 96 above) at 983. 141 After all, fair equality of opportunity implies a right to education, and that right entails ‘subsistence or health or freedom from extreme environmental deprivation,’ for without them, ‘how could educational offerings effectuate fair equality of opportunity?’ Idem at 989. So too, the ‘[e]njoyment of basic liberties’ like freedom of speech has ‘fairly straightforward and objective biological entailments,’ which spell subsistence and the other insurance rights. Finally, the ‘preeminent good of self-respect may imply welfare rights reaching beyond those biological entailments,’ although Michelman does not explore how: idem at 990. 142 Michelman may have been the first sympathetic critic of Rawls to suggest that the difference principle and the income guarantee it entailed were not the only nor the most compelling principle that could be derived from Rawls’s original position A just wants principle might fit the bill better. For a thoughtful later read- ing, canvassing the critics and making these points in greater detail, see J Waldron, Liberal Rights: Collected Papers 1981-1991 (1993) at 250-70. 9 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E my. Rawls devotes great attention in A Theory of Justice to just this subject; what he writes makes plain, I think, that he would include constitutional baselines respecting work and par- ticipation in the economic order, as well as welfare. Despite the tension he uncovers between the primary good of self-respect and the ‘more is bet- ter’ attitude of the difference principle applied to income, Michelman is right in suggesting that the difference principle is concerned with the social bases of self-respect and mutual respect. Indeed, it concerns them more than it does the rational actor’s calculus of consent regarding income shares. When Rawls writes about consent, he is concerned about what it takes to make each person a consenting member a charter member of society. He is concerned not only, or even primarily, with rational choice, but with contract, undertaking, and commitment143 more pre- cisely, with consent and commitment to the social enterprise, and, conversely, with the conditions which turn consent and commitment into submission and subjection. This is the problem Rawls dubs the ‘strains of commitment.’144 Under an unjust political economy, such as ours, there are millions of citizens who cannot plausibly see themselves as members of a political community organized in their name to promote their interests and capacities. Instead of supporting their capacities for commitment we have strained them to a breaking point. What, then, are the political-economic bases of consent and commitment? More important, writes Rawls, than ‘a high material standard of life’145 in securing ‘a just and good society … is meaningful work in free association with others, these associations regulating their relations to one another within a framework of just basic institutions.’146 That is why, as you will recall, the difference principle reaches beyond income to the distribution of wealth and power; it concerns shared authority no less than a fair share of goods. This is the key difference between Rawls’s con- stitutional political economy which he dubs a ‘property-owning democracy’147 and the political economy of the welfare state. ‘In a welfare state,’ he writes in a 1987 preface to A Theory of Justice, ‘the aim [of political institutions] is that none should fall below a decent standard of life … . By contrast, in a property-owning democracy the aim is to carry out the idea of society as a fair system of cooperation over time between citizens as free and equal persons.’148 The ‘back- ground institutions of property-owning democracy … try to disperse the ownership of wealth and capital, and thus to prevent a small part of society from controlling the economy and indirectly political life itself.’149 ‘The idea is not simply to assist those who lose out through accident or mis- fortune (although this must be done), but instead to put all citizens in a position to manage their own affairs and to take part in social cooperation on a footing of mutual respect … .’150 In a word, Rawls’s precepts for political economy fall squarely within the social citizenship tra- dition. His political economy of citizenship bears a strong family resemblance to those of the Populists, Progressives, and New Dealers who fashioned the variants of social citizenship thought in America. Like them, he holds that one cannot be a consenting, charter member, a ‘citizen,’ of 143 Rawls (note 8 above) at 176: ‘[W]hen we enter an agreement we must be able to honor it even should the worst possibilities prove to be the case… . Thus the parties must weigh with care whether they will be able to stick by their commitment in all circumstances.’ 144 Idem at 145, 176, 423. For a thoughtful discussion of this theme in Rawls, see Waldron (note 142 above) at 259-63. 145 Rawls (note 8 above) at 290. 146 Idem. 147 J Rawls ‘Preface for the French Edition of A Theory of Justice’ in Samuel Freeman (ed) Collected Papers (1999) 415 at 419. 148 Idem. 149 Idem. 150 Idem. the national community without decent work, a measure of economic independence, and at least a small share of authority over the governance of one’s work and shared economic life. Whether one rests one’s normative claim for welfare rights on some variant of Rawlsian liberal- ism, as Michelman does in the work we have been considering, or one relies on the republican tra- dition, as he does in the essays we take up later, a key part of the argument for welfare rights is this: These rights are necessary to secure the social bases of self-respect (the main concern in Rawls) and of independence and mutual respect or equal standing (republicanism’s primary emphasis). In sum, welfare rights are necessary to a liberal republican (or, if you prefer, a republican liberal) concep- tion of equal citizenship. Yet, plainly the social bases of equal citizenship consist of more than a decent minimum of food, shelter, and other material needs. They also demand a right to earn a livelihood through decent work; they require an opportunity to contribute in some recognized fash- ion to the social enterprise as well as to civic and political life. This broader view of the material dimensions of constitutional equality has a better mooring in the empirical literature that treats the social and economic underpinnings of self-respect151 and mutual respect152 among women and men in today’s America and a better mooring in our constitutional history. (B) JUSTICIABILITY — A CONCERN FOR JUDICIAL COMPETENCE AND LEGITIMACY The family resemblance we found between Rawls and earlier proponents of social citizenship is one that critics like Sandel studiously smudge over, in order to claim that Rawls has aban- doned the ‘formative’ project of developing good citizens.153 Michelman is as careful and gen- erous a reader as dwells in the republic of letters; he does not smudge over these aspects of Rawls’s political economy, but openly puts them aside to carry on with ‘minimum protection’ and constitutional welfare rights. Probably Michelman would have invoked justiciability as rea- son enough to have put other social citizenship norms to one side, both in reading Rawls and in his own constitutional theorizing. ‘Justiciability,’ indeed, was Michelman’s reason for seek- ing insurance rights, even though he conceded that it was ‘easier and more natural to find in Rawls [a right to a] guaranteed money income’154 or, more generally, a ‘right[] against exces- sive or unnecessary inequality of wealth or income.’155 Justiciability has two dimensions here. Frank Michelman on Social Rights 93 151 See eg WJ Wilson When Work Disappears: The World of the New Urban Poor (1996); AH Goldsmith et al ‘The Psychological Impact of Unemployment and Joblessness’ (1996) 25 J Socio-Eco 333; A Sen The Penalties of Unemployment (Banca D’Italia Working Paper No 307 1997). 152 Of course, complex patterns of respect, deference, and degradation form around class and occupational hierar- chies, but all the empirical literature suggests that the most salient border between minimum respect and degra- dation in today’s class structure falls along the line between those who are recognized by organized society as working and providing a decent living for themselves and their families, and those men and women at the bot- tom of the nation’s class hierarchy who are not. See eg JF Handler & Y Hasenfeld We the Poor People: Work, Poverty, and Welfare (1997); KS Newman, No Shame in My Game: The Working Poor in the Inner City (1999). On the experience of women in regard to the identities of housewife and ‘[waged] working woman’ and the dilemmas of self-respect and social recognition as a full and equal member of American society, see V Schultz ‘Life’s Work’ (2000) 100 Col LR 1881 at 1883 (arguing that for women, no less than men, the right to par- ticipate in decent work is indispensable to equal citizenship; canvassing empirical literature showing that ‘a robust conception of equality [for women] can be best achieved through paid work, rather than despite it.’). 153 MJ Sandel Democracy’s Discontent: America in Search of a Public Philosophy 6 (1996); see MJ Sandel Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (1982); Rawls (note 8 above) at 259 (noting that not only their capac- ity for self-respect but more broadly ‘the sort of persons [citizens] want to be as well as the sort of persons they are’ are shaped by the political economy they live under). 154 Michelman (note 96 above) at 966. 155 Idem. 9 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E The first concerns institutional capacity, or ‘judicial competence’ in legal process-ese. The sec- ond concerns the degree to which a given norm is formally law-like, determinate, and objective in its application. This dimension of justiciability obtains whether the setting is the courtroom, the legislature, or the constitutional convention, when ‘constitutional amendment is the chosen avenue of reform.’156 In any of these fora, one must be concerned that the norms one is craft- ing or deriving from more general constitutional texts are such norms about which one can say with some measure of certainty that this constitutional requirement has or has not been or is or is not in the process of being met. Begin with judicial competence. Here, surely the starting point must be ‘compared to what?’ Is a right to decent work any more beyond judicial capacities or more insulting to separation of powers constraints than the rights to welfare, health care, and decent housing with which Michelman conjures? With the former as with the latter, a number of competency and separa- tion of powers concerns arise, and a variety of judicial strategies are open. The concerns and the strategies are familiar, and Michelman briefly surveys several.157 ‘[P]erplexing questions of economic feasibility’158 may arise; a decree fulfilling a ‘claimed housing [or employment] right [might] leav[e] the bottom worse off, on the whole, than it now is.’159 But, says Michelman, such questions ‘do not seem different in essence from other issues that courts have deemed judicially triable.’160 And in respect of housing and school finance, as well as other social citizenly matters, judicial experience has grown since 1973, particularly if one takes account of developments abroad and in America’s state courts.161 Courts have found credible ways to assess claims of glaring failure on the part of national and subnational governments to address and meet guarantees of social rights. But it must be admitted that this body of constitutional (as distinct from statutory-interpretive) judicial experience has not addressed work and employment; and certainly, it is plausible that the many-sided determinants of the availability of decent work might counsel against a judicial role in interpreting and enforcing this as opposed to other social rights. I want to leave this possibility hanging, to be revisited when more of Michelman’s and my own thoughts about judicial and non-judicial interpretation and enforcement of social rights are on the table. ‘More plausible’ than the argument for adjudicative incompetence, notes Michelman, ‘is the notion of remedial incompetence.’162 Courts have no way of enforcing social rights without the raising and appropriating of public funds and the creation of new administrative structures. Such actions are not only under the control of the other branches, but also ‘involve[] a complex of subsidiary but vitally important choices which the judiciary lacks all basis for making.’163 156 Idem at 967. 157 See idem at 1004-10. 158 Idem at 1006. 159 Michelman (note 96 above) at 1006. 160 Idem. 161 Fior a chastened but positive assessment of judicial contributions in the education financing arena, see M Minow ‘Just Education: An Essay for Frank Michelman’ (2004) 39 Tulsa LR 547. On the South African Constitutional Court’s interventions in the domain of housing, see Michelman ‘Constitution and Social Rights’ (note 9 above) at 17-18, 26-27. Most strikingly, perhaps, has been the work of German constitu- tional courts, at both the national and subnational levels, in respect of constitutional rights to housing and to a decent livelihood. See PE Quint ‘The Constitutional Guarantees of Social Welfare in the Process of German Unification’ (1999) 47 Am J Comp L 303. For a general discussion of constitutional adjudicato- ry experience with social rights, see C Fabre Social Rights under the Constitution: Government and the Decent Life (2000) 152-81. 162 Michelman (note 96 above) at 1006. 163 Idem. One response to this problem is ‘a judicial mandate to legislative, executive, or administrative officers to prepare, submit, and carry out a corrective plan.’164 Separation of powers presents a different order of concern. Here, Rawlsian principles, on Michelman’s account, may collide. Judicial vindication of substantive welfare rights may come at too high a cost ‘in participatory inequality [as between the judiciary’s and the citizenry’s respective roles in identifying the social rights to which a society’s shared principles of justice commit it] which damages [the citizen’s] self-respect.’165 The trade-off between ‘justice in par- ticipatory rights and justice in substantive rights,’166 may demand judicial forbearance. Or at least, it may demand that courts ‘not cut welfare rights out of the whole cloth of speculative moral theory.’167 Likewise, I’d add, for the same reason, courts ought to forebear from cutting social citizenship rights out of the whole cloth of interpretative recollection of extra-judicial constitutional tradition. But such judgments do not exhaust the question of whether judges should ever allow such a theory to inform their application of ‘due process and equal protection guaranties in their formal and non-substantive aspects’168 to statutory materials. Here Michelman takes inspi- ration from the lower federal courts’ pre-Dandridge readiness to find in equal protection a command to invalidate even seemingly plausible classifications among potential eligibles169 and generally to put the statutory programs’ limitations and qualifications under strain, in the name of making need alone the valid criterion. Too, he finds in cases like King v Smith studies of how courts can find in AFDC and kindred legislation statutory rights that amounted to ‘justice-inspired [legislative] supplementation of the constitutional cata- logue.’170 Certainly, this is a credible way to interpret the Court’s reading of Congress’s intent against the grain of legislative history and of Congress’s knowing acquiescence in state practices the Court went on to condemn. Unprepared to declare the existence of such a constitutional right (and so openly and irrevocably to constrain Congress), the Court nonetheless was prepared to expand and deepen the limited and qualified commitments Congress had made. Not only is this a plausible reconstruction of the interaction between Court and Congress, but it is suggestive of how a judiciary mindful of the constitutional dimensions of work and par- ticipation could read statutory material in the area of labor and employment.171 In the case of statutory work and employment rights, however, a court would not need to rely on ‘enlight- ened,’ emergent, contemporary notions of democracy and justice. Nudging state or federal agencies to construe their congressional mandates in ways that leaned toward inclusion or actu- al availability of work opportunities, courts could proceed in a somewhat more conservative interpretative style, relying on old, not emerging or ‘enlightened’ elite understandings of equal rights and constitutional equality. Frank Michelman on Social Rights 95 164 Idem. 165 Idem at 1010. 166 Idem. 167 Michelman (note 96 above) at 1010. 168 Idem. 169 See idem at 1011-12. 170 Idem at 1011. 171 For a like-minded account of possible readings of the Wagner Act see M Barenberg ‘Democracy and Domination in the Law of Workplace Cooperation: From Bureaucratic to Flexible Production’ (1994) 94 Col LR 753. 9 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E (C) JUSTICIABILITY AND PROBLEMS OF INDETERMINACY AND OF CONSTRAINTS ON DEMOCRACY IN PUBLIC POLITICAL FORA ‘In Search of Constitutional Welfare Rights’ holds that welfare rights are the best vocabulary for expressing a constitutional commitment to a social minimum, partly by dint of their sup- posedly greater crispness and formal, determinate applicability. Donning the hat of counselor to hypothetical constitution-framers, Michelman says this: If you want to lay a basis for ‘con- vincing [constitutional] advocacy in political forums,’172 then state your commitment to a social minimum in the form of ‘insurance rights.’173 To rely on a more Rawlsian vocabulary ‘would [fail to] give … advocates any special foothold for challenging legislative judgments.’174 Of course, here Michelman is comparing insurance rights to Rawls’s difference principle. The comparison that interests us, however, is a different one. Is the legal-rhetorical foothold supplied by a right to decent housing any more secure from contending interpretations than that provided by a right to decent work? We need not belabor the point. Michelman concedes it in a recent engagement with the arguments I am raising here. ‘If we … compare a social-citizenship conception with a welfare-right conception of a pos- itive constitutional guarantee in the economic sphere, we can see that neither sort of concep- tion trumps the other on the scale of justiciability.’175 Indeed, the examples Michelman choos- es are those we’ve been employing. He points to the welfare right found in the present South African Constitution, ‘to have access to adequate housing,’ a welfare right whose ‘progressive realization’ the state must take ‘reasonable’ steps ‘to achieve.’176 And he asks whether such a right registers any higher on the scale of justiciability ‘than would a declared duty of the state to do the best it can to maintain an economy and society in which everyone who wants it has access to respectable, fulfilling, adequately remunerated work.’177 The answer, he concedes, is no.178 If the welfare-right conception has an edge in respect of ‘concerns about constitutional-legal form,’179 it is on the scale of what Michelman now calls ‘narrowness.’180 This is a concern dis- tinct from justiciability. It does not concern courts’ remedial competence or democratic deficits, nor whether a given norm is too general and wide-open-to-competing-interpretations. Rather, it concerns how widely or narrowly a norm ‘preempt[s] major public policy choices from the ordinary politics of democratic debate and decision.’181 More than a welfare right, ‘a constitu- tional social-citizenship right … reach[es] in a hundred directions … into the deepest redoubts of the common law and the most basic choices of political economy a modern society can make.’182 Certainly, if my historical scholarship is right about the way these rights have figured in pub- lic political discourse and debate about everything from currency to education to industrial 172 Michelman (note 96 above) at 1002. 173 Idem. 174 Idem at 1003. 175 See Michelman ‘Democracy-Based Resistance’ (note 9 above) at 1896. 176 Idem. 177 Idem. 178 See idem. 179 Idem at 1895. 180 See Michelman ‘Democracy-Based Resistance’ (note 9 above) at 1895-96. 181 Idem at 1895. 182 Idem at 1897. organization, then Michelman is right. And note: Michelman’s point pertains independently of the scope of judicial enforceability, as long as we presume our public officials to be conscien- tious. Here, Michelman’s thinking merges with the social citizenship tradition’s conception of how its norms would bear on democratic lawmaking—not via judicial review, but instead by directly constraining participants and the standards they apply and the arguments they offer in debates and decisions about public policy-making. Over against the charge of non- ’narrowness’ or democracy-stymieing, Michelman offers a defense on behalf of social citi- zenship norms. It is precisely the ‘blatant “non-justiciability” of a social-citizenship right its utter lack of mechanical applicability to any hard or contested question of public policy … [that] saves it from charges of contrariety to democracy.’183 Instead of thwarting democra- cy, social citizenship norms would mark a ‘gain for democracy … [by] impos[ing] a certain constraint on how citizens and their elected representatives would frame and approach sundry questions of public policy.’184 That is, the norms would demand of all concerned an ‘exercise[] of … judgment … [about] which choice will best conduce to the social citizen- ship of everyone.’185 By invoking Michelman present to respond to Michelman past, we have strayed from Michel- man on Rawls and welfare rights in 1973. The burden of this foray into the present has been to suggest that Michelman’s insistence on the justiciability of social and economic rights in non- judicial fora was a product of the politics and doctrine of the day. Today, doctrine and politics afford neither the same possibilities nor their concomitant constraints, and we do better to pur- sue the path of social citizenship down which Rawls and our home-grown ideals of social citi- zenship direct us. Or as Michelman observes in reference to a fuller version of the criticisms lev- eled here, if we count ourselves among those who ‘maintain that constitutional law outside the courts can figure importantly in the conduct of public affairs [and] that contention outside the courts over constitutional-legal meanings and obligations very possibly can be … a site for democracy in action,’186 then should we not put justiciability issues aside, and ask: ‘Is there any reason why we who take this view should hesitate to embrace a social-citizenship conception of constitutional social rights, in preference to a welfare-right conception, assuming we find the former to be morally the more appealing conception?’187 There is more to say about the interaction of social-citizenship norms and democratic politics and lawmaking, and more of Michelman’s insights and qualms to consider. We may yet conclude that a sparer set of social rights, a set of social minima, ought to enjoy constitutional pride of place, over against the broader, more historically rooted, and, perhaps, ‘morally … more appeal- ing’ social-citizenship conception that I have put forward. We may yet conclude that judicial safe- guards should obtain for essential welfare rights but not for the social citizenship principle. And we may find ourselves, with Michelman, in the grip of genuine dilemmas. But further consider- ation should await a reading of Michelman’s republican case for welfare rights. This brings us to his turn to history, and his thoughtful reading of Progressive constitutionalism. Frank Michelman on Social Rights 97 183 Idem at 1898. 184 Idem. 185 Michelman ‘Democracy-Based Resistance’ (note 9 above) at 1898 (emphasis omitted). 186 Michelman ‘Constitution and Social Rights’ (note 9 above) at 28. 187 Idem at 28-29. 9 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E V Michelman’s Republican Case for Welfare Rights (A) THE DISTRIBUTIVE DIMENSION OF CONSTITUTIONAL PROPERTY RIGHTS AND THE PROBLEM OF LEGAL FORM By the late 1970s, the Court had begun to cut the solicitous strands of doctrine well short of substantive welfare rights, declaring ever more categorically that its Constitution confers ‘no affirmative right to governmental aid, even where such aid may be necessary to secure life, lib- erty, or property … .’188 Liberal constitutional scholarship grew more theoretical as the Court grew more conservative. Theorists acknowledged the limits of judicial competence and legiti- macy in the area of affirmative rights. They began to reflect on the ‘gap between the reach of constitutional case law and the reach of the Constitution.’189 They built up more general, less court-centered accounts of constitutional democracy as a system of self-government. For his part, Michelman made civic republicanism and contemporary pragmatism and criti- cal theory his own, and brought them into an internal dialogue with liberal constitutional the- ory. Out of this emerged a profound series of reflections on the dilemmas of constitutional self- government, the tensions between popular sovereignty and the rule of law, the nature of adju- dication, and, most germane here, the ‘possessive’ and ‘distributive’ conceptions of constitu- tional property rights.190 Written in 1986, Michelman’s exploration of the tensions between these two kinds of property norms sets out to reconstruct the republican logic and history of the distributive side of constitutional property claims, to suggest why this side has been the recessive one in constitutional law, and to join issue with those, like Michael Walzer, who object for staunchly democratic reasons to the constitutionalization of ‘welfare claims as rights.’191 Michelman seized hold of the founders’ venerable republican conviction that ‘security of proper- ty holdings was [not just a matter of] private self-interest’;192 it was ‘of general political concern.’193 Material independence was ‘viewed as indispensable if one’s independence and competence as a par- ticipant in public affairs was to be guaranteed.’194 This maxim had obvious bearing on the anti- redistributive, property-protecting provisions in the founders’ Constitution; but it also implied a dis- tributive imperative. This imperative, too, found support in much that the founders wrote and did. But it found no obvious expression in the provisions and architecture of their Constitution. The dis- tributive norm was deferred, Michelman suggests. Given the prospect of westward expansion, the founding generation could envision ‘a freehold beneath every household … supporting the free- holder’s independence.’195 As long as this state of affairs continued, the Constitution’s possessive regard for property was sufficient to answer the founders’ distributive concerns. 188 DeShaney v Winnebago City Dept of Social Services 489 US at 196. 189 See LG Sager ‘Justice in Plain Clothes: Reflections on the Thinness of Constitutional Law’ (1993) 88 Nw U LR 410 at 419. 190 See eg FI Michelman ‘Conceptions of Democracy in American Constitutional Argument: Voting Rights’ (1989) 41 Fla LR 443; FI Michelman ‘Law’s Republic’ (1988) 97 Yale LJ 1493; FI Michelman ‘‘Possession vs. Distribution’ in the Constitutional Idea of Property’ (1987) 72 Iowa LR 1319 [hereinafter Michelman ‘Possession vs. Distribution’]; FI Michelman ‘Foreword: Traces of Self-Government’ (1986) 100 Harv LR 4; Radin & Michelman (note 12 above). 191 Michelman ‘Possession vs. Distribution’ (note 190 above) at 1320-21. The essay by Michael Walzer which Michelman addresses is M Walzer ‘Philosophy and Democracy’ (1981) 9 Pol Theory 379. 192 Michelman ‘Possession vs. Distribution’ (note 190 above) at 1329. 193 Idem (emphasis omitted). 194 Idem at 1329. 195 Idem at 1332. By the end of the nineteenth century, however, a ‘Progressive critique’ of this constitutional arrangement had emerged. With the rise of industrial capitalism, a regime of anti-redistributive property rights – so the critique ran – might itself ‘constitute undemocratic relationships of power and subjection.’196 On this account, persons—wage earners, tenant farmers, and others ’subject- ed to the proprietary power of others lacked … the material foundations of independent political competence.’197 In short, with the rise of large-scale corporate enterprise and its impact on the legal-political-intellectual culture of the late nineteenth century, the distributive and anti-redis- tributive sides of our tradition’s constitutional understanding of property claims were set on a col- lision course. Once it was firmly recognized that ‘uncontrolled so-called private power’198 expos- es individuals to subjection, it behooved government to act. ‘Logically, however, the state cannot offer protection … by the same formal law that would protect absolutely against redistributive political “interventions.”’199 Accordingly, while the Progressive critique largely succeeded in undoing the regime of anti-redistributive property norms, it did not succeed, on Michelman’s account, in supplanting those norms with distributive ones. Indeed, Michelman implies that the Progressive reformers never sought to embed such distributive norms into constitutional dis- course. They hardly could have hoped to do so, it appears in his view, since distributive norms, whatever their claim to constitutional status, seem to place an unbearable burden on our com- mitment to formally realizable, objective, ‘law’-like standards as the sole, legitimate lingua franca in the province and discourse of the Constitution.200 As you might guess, I am on all fours with Michelman and he with me all the way to the last point. There, as an historical and interpretative matter, we seem to part ways in modest degree; for I read the Progressives, and their forebears and descendants, stretching from the 1880s to the 1940s generations of reformers which, following Michelman, for present purposes, I’ll sim- ply call Progressives somewhat differently. As I’ve encountered them in years of reading, these generations of Progressives found no insoluble tension inherent in the effort to ‘cast substan- tively appealing and defensible distributive norms’201 as constitutional standards. They did not neglect ‘the classical negative understanding of fundamental rights’202 (in the thick of Lochnerism, how could they?), nor the appeal that understanding made to a deep-seated image of constitutional norms as ‘strongly objective’ abstract, simple, formal and, thereby, law-like. But they treated the grip of these ideas on ‘the American constitutional imagination’203 as con- tingent and contestable via tools Michelman knows well: pragmatism, context, a ‘changing Constitution.’ Thus, as I’ve shown elsewhere in needlepoint detail, their view was this: the need to make the constitutional tradition’s distributive imperatives into direct claims against the state did not compel divorcing constitutional from political economic discourse; it did demand dethroning the courts and installing Congress and the ‘active branches’ as the nation’s new ‘constitutional political economists.’204 In tandem with this reallocation of interpretive authority, I’ve shown how Progressives set Frank Michelman on Social Rights 99 196 Idem at 1335. 197 Michelman ‘Possession vs. Distribution’ (note 190 above) at 1335. 198 Idem. 199 Idem at 1336. 200 Idem at 1337. 201 Idem at 1321. 202 Michelman ‘Possession vs. Distribution’ (note 190 above) at 1321 (quoting DP Currie ‘Positive and Negative Constitutional Rights’ (1986) 53 U Chi LR 864 at 889) (internal quotations omitted). 203 Idem. 204 See Forbath ‘Caste, Class, and Equal Citizenship’ (note 7 above) at 51-57. 1 0 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E about the hermeneutic task of translating ‘the “old and sacred possessive [common-law based and anti-redistributive] rights” of property and labor’205 into new ‘social and economic rights,’ to enable ‘“a return to values lost in the course of … economic development” and “a recovery” of the “old rights” once robust social meaning.’206 The ‘active branches’ and the citizenry itself, so Progressives and, later, New Dealers contended, were better suited to the task of interpret- ing and applying the new ‘social meaning’ of constitutional property norms in part for the kinds of justiciability reasons Michelman highlights, but also because they sought to advance a more dialogic and democratic mode of constitutional interpretation and decisionmaking. Interestingly, if I am right about this history, I do no more than provide an ancestry for the revisionist aspect of Michelman’s argument about the forms of constitutional law and demo- cratic politics.207 Michelman’s urging is this: If we can but relax the hold of our inherited ideal of legality in favor of a revised and more pragmatic one, then we might open the space for a fuller consideration of ‘distributive property claims … [in] the province[] and discourse[] of constitutional law.’208 (B) REPUBLICANISM VS WELFARE RIGHTS Perhaps because his attention rests so largely upon the seeming tension between distributive norms and ‘legal’ ones, and perhaps because his proof text is Walzer’s critique of the idea of constitutional legalization of welfare rights, the latter remains Michelman’s only specification of what a modern distributive constitutional property claim deserving of our more ample con- sideration might be. As a result, another, perhaps equally deep, tension goes unexplored. That is the tension between the modern welfare rights claim and the republican underpinning Michelman claims for it. Republican maxims hold that a measure of material independence is a necessary basis for polit- ical competence and standing. That is Michelman’s normative baseline. But in the republican out- look he invokes, such citizenly standing and competence have always been bound up with the sta- tus of one who fulfills some recognized, responsible role in the social enterprise – one who ‘earns’ her measure of material security and ‘independence.’209 We certainly may find, as far back as the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, support in both ‘liberal’ and ‘republican’ texts for the view 205 Idem at 69 (quoting FD Roosevelt ‘Message to Congress Reviewing the Broad Objectives and Accomplishments of the Administration (June 8 1934)’ in The Public Papers and Addresses of Franklin D Roosevelt (1938) 291-92). 206 Idem (quoting same) (internal quotations omitted). Nor were these reform thinkers unmindful of the prob- lem Michelman identifies of mediating between distributive and possessive property claims. See Michelman ‘Possession vs. Distribution’ (note 190 above) at 1321. Progressive reformers like Brandeis and Commons devoted vast attention to reconciling the various possessive property claims of employers with such social rights as minimum livelihoods and unemployment insurance and with the claims of employees, as of right, to a voice in the governance of the enterprise. It is true, though, that their efforts at reconciliation, while principled, did not take the form of ‘strongly objective standards’ but were rather more contextual and pragmatic. See eg JR Commons Legal Foundations of Capitalism (1924). 207 Ancestors who were, at least until World War I, largely blind to what we now know—and what post-war Progressives began to surmise—about the democratic resources in rights, ‘higher law,’ and judicial authority. 208 Michelman ‘Possession vs. Distribution’ (note 190 above) at 1324. 209 See WE Forbath ‘The Ambiguities of Free Labor: Labor and the Law in the Gilded Age’ (1985) Wis LR 767 (tracing this theme in republican discourse of political and legal elites and labor reformers in US from 1780s to 1880s); Forbath ‘Caste, Class, and Equal Citizenship’ (note 7 above) at 13-15, 18-19) 26-51 (same, adding inflections of theme in women’s, African American, and agrarian movements, and carrying forward into 1890s-1930s). that the poor have a subsistence claim on society’s resources. In truth, that claim was well-defend- ed by Locke; it is there, too, in the writings of Adam Smith.210 But that is a far cry from making this longstanding claim a basis for citizenship in the sense of full membership in the political com- munity. Neither Locke, nor Smith, nor Madison and Jefferson in the ‘republican’ texts Michelman relies on,211 nor later renderings of liberalism and republicanism, up to and including Professors Rawls and Sandel – none of these lend support to the idea of making public assistance simpliciter the material base of citizenship. That base, that dignifying social minimum, must rest on some socially recognized contribution on a person’s part to the common enterprise. VI Welfare vs Social Citizenship Rights (A) THUS FAR: THE SOCIAL-CITIZENSHIP CONCEPTION IS THE BETTER ONE This broader, more participatory conception of social citizenship may not be necessary in every lib- eral democratic society today to assure a person’s standing as an ‘equal participant in public affairs.’ But to use a phrase with which Michelman recently has conjured, this account seems firmly embed- ded in America’s ‘constitutional identity.’212 The longstanding links between work, equal respect, and citizenship seem constitutive of ‘who we think we are and aim to be as a politically constitut- ed people, [of] where we think we have come from and where we think we are headed.’213 The idea that welfare rights fit well with either a liberal or a republican understanding of the material bases of equal citizenship was first forged in the context of the welfare rights movement, as a scholar’s contribution to that inspiring struggle. But the movement, like any social movement of subordinate people, was sharply constrained. It played the hand that history and the White House dealt it. Its programmatic vision, its strategy and goals, all were shaped by the social provi- sion and institutional resources at hand to address black poverty AFDC, LSO, and the Community Action Agencies. But nothing about this conjuncture gave any assurance that welfare rights were the right solution to the problem of social and economic exclusion confronting poor black citizens. Black leaders like King and Rustin plainly thought otherwise; they called for a ‘Negroes’ New Deal’ that emphasized decent work. As a normative matter, and as a constitutional one, I have suggest- ed, they were right. Frank Michelman on Social Rights 101 210 Regarding Locke, see eg, J Locke Two Treatises of Government 170 (1960) (poor man has a right to ‘Title to so much out of another’s Plenty as will keep him from extreme want’); TA Horne Property Rights and Poverty: Political Argument in Britain, 1605-1834 (1990) at 48-65; and R Ashcraft ‘Liberalism and the Problem of Poverty’ (1992) 6 Crit Rev 493 at 497 (demonstrating that Locke and classical liberalism emphasize natural right to subsistence; they see ‘poor relief [as a] constitutive and necessary feature of any legitimate society’). Regarding Smith, see eg A Smith An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations (1950) 80 (‘No society can surely be flourishing … of which the far greater part of the members are poor and miserable.’); I Hont & M Ignatieff, Needs and Justice in the Wealth of Nations: An Introductory Essay, in Wealth and Virtue: The Shaping of Political Economy in the Scottish Enlightenment (1983) 1 (identifying meeting needs of poor as Smith’s theoretical axis for assessing political-economic arrangements). 211 For a Madison or Jefferson, poor relief left paupers still ‘dependent’ and, therefore, unqualified for citizen- ship. They favored ample material opportunities (they even occasionally championed rights to property in ‘full and absolute dominion’) for all white men willing and able to exploit them, and charity or coercion for the rest. See Forbath ‘Caste, Class, and Equal Citizenship’ (note 7 above) at 13-14 (discussing and quot- ing from the Madison and Jefferson texts relied on by Michelman and other ‘Constitutional Welfare Rights’ defenders like Sunstein). 212 See FI Michelman ‘Morality, Identity and ‘Constitutional Patriotism’’ (1999) 76 Denv U LR 1009 at 1025. 213 Idem. 1 0 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E The vision of citizenship fashioned by the welfare rights movement also was shaped by the fact that the movement’s constituents were women and mothers. King and Rustin had nothing to say about this fact, and precious little to say about gender equality in general. But everything we know about welfare and work suggests that generous and guaranteed welfare provision – however morally imperative it may be – cannot do the main work of securing gender equality for poor women. That also demands reconstructing the low wage labor market, striving to assure decent jobs for women, no less than men, and providing enabling rights, as well, to train- ing and child care and old-age pensions, as well as provision and incentives that enable and encourage equitable sharing of dependent-care. A liberal society that prizes the dignity of the individual, if it is an affluent one that can afford a guaranteed income that protects all against desperate want, must do so. To refuse is, in Rawls’s terms, to put an unbearable and unjust strain on individuals’ commitments to the social compact. But that is not enough. Equal citizenship also requires social citizenship. Or, as Michelman most recently put the claim on our joint behalf: [We cannot] call on everyone … to submit their fates to a democratic-majoritarian lawmaking system, without also committing our society, from the start, to run itself in ways designed to constitute and sustain every person as a competent and respect- ed contributor to political exchange and contestation and furthermore to social and economic life at large.214 Once one embraces the view that the Constitution must vouchsafe the minimum social conditions of democratic lawmaking, one cannot leave the question of social citizenship where Michelman first left it in his Rawlsian and republican arguments. One cannot leave the work- and economic- independence-and-participation-related aspects of social citizenship to the give and take of ordi- nary politics. Specification of what counts as decent work or recognized but non-waged contri- bution (such as child- or elder-care), and how, at a particular time, the nation ought to go about assuring such opportunities to all, of what counts as a decent livelihood at said time, of what counts as incapacity, and of what quantum of income should separate those, not incapacitated, who avail themselves of ‘welfare’ or a guaranteed income versus those who ‘work’ all these issues and more may and, practically, must be addressed through political and market processes. But if social citizenship guarantees are prerequisites to political equality, then, at the most general level, these commitments must precede ordinary politics; otherwise, a broad swathe of the citizenry would be denied as today they are denied a constitutionally fair opportunity to act as citizen-par- ticipants in the very debates and decisionmaking upon which their citizenly standing depends. As I’ve noted, Michelman, in his most recent work on constitutional social rights, seems to sign on to the ‘Forbath-style constitutional guarantee of social citizenship.’215 In that work, he rehearses the justiciability issues, which had preoccupied him in his first, 1973, engagement with Rawls. These problems of ‘judicial role and competence’ he says, should be the ‘least of our concerns.’216 ‘Judges who know their business … can find both properly adjudicative standards for testing claims of social-rights violations and worthwhile, properly judicial remedies for violations when found.’217 214 Michelman ‘Constitution and Social Rights’ (note 9 above) at 25. 215 Idem at 27; see idem at 29 fn 61 (noting the ‘persuasive case for the moral superiority of the social-citi- zenship conception’). 216 Idem at 13. 217 Idem at 15 (footnote omitted). Courts, therefore, ‘exercising constitutional review in entirely convention- (B) A NEW DILEMMA: DOES THE SOCIAL CITIZENSHIP CONCEPTION REQUIRE ABANDONING JUSTICIABILITY? More troubling than justiciability, Michelman argues, are two other sorts of objections. One is the problem of constraining democratic decision-making, which we’ve already glimpsed; the other objection goes to the ‘non-transparency’ or lack of ‘ascertainability’ of the social citizen- ship guarantee. For a constitutional order to be legitimate, all its core commitments must be such that citizens can see or ascertain that their ‘fellow citizens and their government [are] real- ly complying with [them].’218 Without this quality of ‘transparency’ or ‘ascertainability,’ how could one expect a reasonable citizen reasonably to assent to the constitutional order? The dilemma with the social citizenship guarantee, then, is that it is (a) a prerequisite for a legiti- mate liberal democratic constitution,219 yet, at the same time, (b) deeply problematic in virtue of its ‘raging indeterminacy’ and the fact that, therefore, ‘it will almost always be impossible for anyone to say decisively whether [that guarantee] is or is not being pursued in earnest.’220 In other words, the social citizenship requirement seems to land its proponents in contradiction. The constitutional regime is not legitimate if it does not include the guarantee; but it also is not legitimate if any of its basic guarantees are ‘such that citizens cannot judge whether those guar- antees in fact are being kept, or at least at all times being pursued in good faith.’221 At the end of the day, however, Michelman puts both of these ‘deeper objections’ to the social citizenship guarantee to rest; and he does so through the same device. ‘Rawlsian thought,’ he suggests, ‘offers a way out of this bind’:222 loosening the constitutional requirements of social citizenship from ‘rights’ to ‘directive principles’223 (as that phrase is used in several of the world’s constitutions to denote judicially non-cognizable but nevertheless basic and binding commitments224), or what Rawls would call ‘a constraint on public reason.’225 The upshot is Frank Michelman on Social Rights 103 al, nonworrisome ways almost certainly can play a useful role in the promotion of the distributive aims of social rights guarantees.’ Michelman ‘Constitution and Social Rights’ (note 9 above) at 15. 218 Idem at 31. 219 Idem at 26, 30, 32. 220 Idem at 30. Thus, suppose that ‘effective social citizenship on fair terms for all who seek it’ is, indeed, among the principles to which the government must ‘visibly be committed … in order that the total gover- nance system may be one that meets the … standard’ of constitutional legitimacy – see idem and suppose that lawmakers this year have replaced welfare with workfare, increased by one half the budget allocation for job training, reduced the minimum wage by one-third, extended the collective bargaining laws to cover employers of as few as ten workers, abolished rent control, budgeted an annual sum of 30 billion crowns for housing allowances and job training, increased income tax rates by five percent, reduced the prime lend- ing rate by two percentage points, doubled the size of the employment discrimination mediation corps, and approved a new tariff schedule somewhat less protective than its predecessor, in exchange for reciprocal concessions from abroad. Michelman ‘Constitution and Social Rights’ (note 9 above) at 30-31. Is the gov- ernment complying with the constitutional guarantee of social citizenship? ‘Raging indeterminacy of this sort seems to disqualify a clause like [the social citizenship guarantee] from figuring as a required compo- nent in a complete and legitimating constitutional agreement’: idem at 31. 221 Idem at 32. 222 Idem. 223 Idem. 224 Thus, for example, the Irish Constitution and the Indian Constitution (following the Irish model) both con- tain a list of social rights in a part headed ‘Directive Principles of Social Policy.’ Its opening paragraph states: ‘The principles of social policy set forth in this Article are intended for the general guidance of the [Parliament]. The application of those principles … shall not be cognisable by any Court under any of the provisions of this Constitution’: Art 45, Constitution of Ireland, 1937. 225 Michelman ‘Constitution and Social Rights’ (note 9 above) at 32 fn 65 (quoting and citing Rawls (note 133 at 216-20, 223-27) (internal quotations omitted). 1 0 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E a constitutional order in which ‘the basic negative liberties freedoms of conscience and expres- sion, for example’226 require ‘fully firm, strict, and reliable substantive guarantees of compli- ance,’227 while ‘the rest of social citizenship’228 stands as a requirement that every lawmaker ‘and indeed every voter stands ready … to explain and defend all their votes, on matters affect- ing the structural conditions of social citizenship, as expressions of their honest best judgments about which choice is most conducive to assurance of social citizenship for all … .’229 The dis- tinction Michelman draws between ‘the basic negative liberties’ and ‘the rest of social citizen- ship’ makes plain that by ‘the rest of social citizenship’ he here means not only the right to decent work or other rights we have labeled participatory, but rather all affirmative social rights including ‘welfare’ rights.230 This shift from rights to directive principles seems to put Michelman’s answers to his three objections in conflict with one another. Michelman’s answer to the judicial overreaching objec- tion is to underscore that courts can play a modest but valuable role in securing social rights, while abiding by more or less determinate, law-like standards for testing rights claims and ordi- nary views about the boundaries of courts’ institutional competence and authority. Michelman’s answer to the democracy- and transparency-based objections is to propose mak- ing social rights into not-rights-but-directive-principles fit not for courts, but for citizens and lawmakers in view of their ‘raging indeterminacy,’ and in virtue of the modest but valuable role that constitutional directive principles can play as ‘constraints on’ or ‘inflections of’ public rea- son and deliberation. In other words, Michelman seems to be ascribing a contradictory nature to the social citizen- ship guarantee. If the guarantee, conceived as ‘a right or set of rights,’ is ‘such that citizens can- not judge whether [they] in fact are being kept,’ then one is hard-pressed to imagine how such ‘a right or set of rights’ could yield judges ‘properly adjudicative standards for testing claims of social-rights violations and worthwhile, properly judicial remedies for violations when found.’ (C) ‘RAGING INDETERMINACY’?: NORMATIVE AND PRACTICAL BASES FOR SORTING SOCIAL CITIZENSHIP INTO RIGHTS AND DIRECTIVE PRINCIPLES There are various possible ways out of this contradiction; the best route may be this. Perhaps, in the absence of statutory specification, some social citizenship norms are and others are not reasonably well-suited for courts to help enforce. This, we saw, was Michelman’s view back in 1973, when he contrasted Rawls’s difference principle, as an equality guarantee, to welfare rights to food, shelter, health care, and education. The latter lent themselves to a measure of judicial enforceability; the former did not. Of late, however, Michelman has embraced enlarg- ing the circle of social rights to include, for example, decent work; and this may have con- tributed to inclining him to the view that judgments about the ‘progressive realization’ or ‘good faith pursuit’ of any and all social rights are imbued with so many controvertible policy choic- es and trade-offs that they ought properly be made by the polity and not the courts. 226 Idem at 32. 227 Idem. 228 Idem. 229 Idem. 230 See Michelman ‘Constitution and Social Rights’ (note 9 above) at 33 (contrasting ‘formal, legal guarantees of … the core, basic negative liberties’ with ‘confidence that public reason … prevails in public decision- making over matters affecting … social citizenship’). But transmuting social rights into judicially non-cognizable directive principles comes at an obvious price; for as Michelman recognizes, courts can play a useful role in promoting (at least some elements of) social citizenship. So, it is worth asking whether there is a case for sorting out social citizenship guarantees into sub-categories of rights and directive principles. With the mediating idea of directive principles in hand, we will not be drawn, as Michelman was in 1973, to conflate the justiciability of a particular element of social citizenship with an answer to the question whether that element carries important constitutional weight and significance. So, let us return to the comparison and contrast between the ‘welfare right’ to housing or shelter and the ‘social-citizenship right’ to decent work. Along some important dimensions of justiciability, we have noted, neither of these rights trumps the other. We also have seen that the availability of decent work is a state of affairs which may have a uniquely large and disparate set of potential pol- icy levers surrounding it, running to everything from childcare and job training to the prime lending rate, tax and tariff policies, public investments and employment, and beyond. This leads Michelman to query whether anyone, including presumably a court, could ‘say decisively whether [the guaran- tee] is or is not being pursued in earnest.’ But practical complexity is not all that may importantly distinguish the social citizenship guarantee from welfare rights, like the right to housing. Practical complexity is linked to complexities of social meaning and of cultural contention and change. What it means to ensure that no member of the community is homeless or without ade- quate shelter is not self-evident; but the range of plausible meanings is vastly more definite and exigent than what it means to ensure ‘decent work’ for all, or to sustain every member as ‘a com- petent and respected contributor to political[,] … social, and economic life at large.’231 (D) IMAGINING WELFARE RIGHTS AND SOCIAL CITIZENSHIP IN AMERICA IN 2020 Imagine an America in the year 2020 constitutionally committed to welfare rights and likewise committed to guaranteeing social citizenship for all. In that America, if some are homeless, they should be entitled to say that the Constitution requires that government act in some fashion to ensure an increase in the supply of available, affordable housing and to ensure emergency shel- ter in the meantime. But if some are ‘jobless,’ say by dint of a rash of outsourcing of jobs over- seas, ought they be entitled to say that the Constitution requires that government act to increase the supply of full-time jobs? Putting all practical difficulties and impediments aside, there would remain the question whether that response vindicating the asserted entitlement to a new ‘full- time’ job would be the only or the best way to sustain those newly jobless Americans as ‘com- petent and respected contributors’ to social and economic life. Many, I am sure, would think not. Posed with this question and a chance to deliberate about it, many Americans would probably observe that too many people are laboring their lives away, and that the overwork of some contributes to the unemployment and poverty of others. They might contend that a better response to the moral and material injuries of joblessness would include a broader distribution of decent work, combined with a compensating social wage in cash, or in health insurance or other goods, so that more Americans had decent work and more Americans also had more time for family, community, and other things besides earning wages. Thus, as polities, large or small, considered how to make good on the social citizenship guar- antee, there surely would be good faith normative disagreement about striking the balance between (a) the freedom-enhancing virtues of ensuring decent, dignified livelihoods through Frank Michelman on Social Rights 105 231 Idem at 25. 1 0 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E income guarantees and publicly funded social insurance and (b) the ‘participation’ and ‘indi- vidual responsibility’ values served by requiring people to ‘earn’ those livelihoods via, say, a greater emphasis on public investment and job creation. More narrowly, many Americans would hold that some part of the joblessness problem— and the loss of social and self-respect joblessness produces might be better addressed by remu- nerating and dignifying the work of child or elder care than by creating new full-time jobs out- side the home. Some might even suggest incentives to encourage men, in particular, to spend more time in those pursuits, and to see them as a fair avenue for fulfilling a part of their role as ‘respected contributors.’232 Finally, many Americans, as always, would contend that access to education and the wherewithal to pursue it are an essential alternative response to jobless- ness, at least for those who aspire to some kind of work for which their present education level has not outfitted them. And this is just a brief sampling of the kind of normative debate, con- testation and change that we have every reason to expect would attend the process of honor- ing a social citizenship guarantee in the year 2020. So, a crucial difference between welfare rights and the broader right of social citizenship lies not simply along the dimension of practical complexity but also along the intersecting dimen- sion of normative indeterminacy. The normative meaning of the social citizenship guarantee seems properly subject to a level of good faith disagreement, contestation and change that is quite different from welfare rights to food, clothing, shelter, or even education. In an America constituted by both kinds of guarantees, the response to homelessness, and the incapacitation and indignity it threatens, must be some kind of home; but the response to the marginality and exclusion threatened by joblessness may rightly be more open-ended. It properly entails ongo- ing revaluation of what we mean by ‘full time’ and ‘work’ and ‘respected contribution.’ And if that is so, then there is good reason to conceptualize welfare rights as rights, and the social cit- izenship guarantee as a directive principle. Welfare rights are suited, in ways we’ve already canvassed, to some non-trivial measure of judi- cial oversight, even though enforcing them to the hilt is well beyond the courts’ domain. Since they are essential to constituting every American as a free and equal member of the polity, it seems folly to forsake the judiciary’s contribution. The social citizenship guarantee is no less essential, but because of the wide-open practical and normative choices encircling it, that guarantee presents dis- tinct and intractable justiciability problems. It makes sense, therefore, to deem it a directive princi- ple. So, Michelman’s recent reliance on ‘Rawlsian thought’ for the idea of transmuting social rights into directive principles or ‘constraints on public reason’ seems to me half right.233 If instead we 232 For acknowledgement by the present Court of the constitutional stakes in ensuring that men bear an equal share of the work of family care, see Nevada Department of Human Resources v Hibbs 123 S Ct 1972 (2003) (holding that because the unequal distribution of family care between women and men contributes to women’s social and economic inequality, public employment practices that perpetuate this inequality amount to constitutional injuries, which Congress is empowered to redress under the Fourteenth Amendment). 233 I note that Rawls himself, in Political Liberalism, did not draw the category of ‘constitutional essentials’ as narrowly as Michelman seems to suggest. In addition to the basic negative liberties like freedom of con- science, Rawls also holds that ‘a social minimum providing for the basic needs of all citizens’ also belongs in the category of ‘constitutional essentials’ requiring fully firm, strict, and reliable substantive guarantees of compliance. See Rawls (note 133 above) at 228-29 & fn 23 (noting that Rawls finds himself ‘accepting Frank Michelman’s view as stated in “Welfare Rights and Constitutional Democracy”’). Thus, what Rawls leaves out of his category of ‘constitutional essentials’ (and puts into the category of principles that instead must serve as ‘constraints on public reason’) seems closer to what I am suggesting: the difference principle and fair equality of opportunity. See idem at 226-29. divvy up the constitutional universe of social rights into rights and directive principles, perhaps, we better serve the competing concerns which prompted Michelman. Such a division might help insure against an obvious danger posed by the full-scale morph- ing of rights into directive principles: while the polity deliberates, and public reason unfolds, people starve. Good faith disagreement shades imperceptibly into dawdling and indifference. And the voices of those at the margins weaken. Judicially cognizable welfare rights might pro- vide a hook and a prod, to use Michelman’s own metaphors, for securing the livelihoods of those at the margins, boosting slightly their ability to participate in the polity’s conversations about its directive principles, about what it means to sustain everyone as a participant and con- tributor. What is more, the simpler we make the cognizable essentials of social citizenship, the more vigorously our constitutional courts might provide stays against political failures. Today, social provision, social rights, even the social safety net are in tatters and disrepute. The working poor constitute a growing part of the nation’s labor force, and the scandal of over- work, demeaning conditions, and impoverishing wages for millions of Americans goes largely unaddressed. During this dry season, no scholar has done more than Michelman to keep intel- lectually alive and vivid the view that high constitutional values and commitments are at stake in how America responds to poverty and material inequality. As we ponder the shape and the practice of social rights and social citizenship in a progressive Constitution for the year 2020, we are lucky to have Frank Michelman to begin the conversation. Frank Michelman on Social Rights 107 The Just Community: Emile Durkheim on Liberalism and Society D E R I K G E L D E R B L O M Department of Sociology, UNISA I Introduction My aim in this chapter is to provide an overview, and evaluation, of an early communitarian critic of liberalism: Emile Durkheim (1858-1917). Durkheim was one of the founders of aca- demic sociology. His work later inspired the functionalist school in anthropology and sociolo- gy. He was also an important forerunner of the structuralist movement of the 1960s and 1970s in France and elsewhere. Durkheim’s contribution towards the debates on liberalism and human rights arose in the context of his lifelong concern to investigate the relationship between individual and society. He tried to reconcile an emphasis on individual freedom with the demands of social integration and justice. This is especially relevant in our current context where the failures of both a collectivist Marxism and an individualist capitalism are all too apparent. In terms of the current debates between liberals and communitarians, he can best be classi- fied as a communitarian. He was especially critical of free-market liberals and their belief that the invisible hand of the market had the capacity to create spontaneous order out of the selfish exchanges of individuals. Although he found much he could agree with in Kant’s epistemology and ethics, he objected to a core point of departure of Kant’s philosophy. He felt that Kant’s emphasis on a transhistorical, autonomous subject of knowledge neglected the social factors in the rise of this subject, and could not give an account of the individual’s dependency on socie- ty. These points all address themes common to the communitarian critique of liberalism. At the same time, however, Durkheim believed that individual freedom and justice were core values that any modern society had to defend. He also did not regard traditional sources of commu- nity such as religion, ethnicity and the family as viable options for a modern society, and believed that new sources of community had to be found. Durkheim’s defence of communitar- ianism was very sophisticated, and deserves better scrutiny in this debate. II The Nature of Rights Durkheim’s critique of free-market liberals relates to their exclusive emphasis on so-called negative rights. An ongoing dispute in human rights discourse (and within the liberal tradition) concerns the nature of the rights that have to be extended to individuals in order to guarantee their liberty.1 One 1 J Christman Social and Political Philosophy. A Contemporary Introduction (2002) at 47, 216 endnote 1. side, nowadays called the libertarians, argue that these are limited to protection against inter- ference from others. In practice this means that the state must protect the life and property of individuals from depredations by others, and otherwise guarantee their freedom to live their life as best as possible. Their opponents, of which John Rawls is within the liberal tradition the most prominent exponent, believes that additional rights are necessary to guarantee the mini- mum level of living necessary to meaningfully exercise those rights (so-called positive rights). This means that the state must act to reduce gross poverty that impedes the self-realisation of some individuals. As is well-known, the South African constitution is relatively unique in the sense that it contains provisions supporting positive rights. It is also common knowledge that, in the Grootboom case, the Constitutional Court has committed itself to an, at least limited, degree of judicial oversight regarding the government’s duty to give effect to those provisions. In Durkheim’s time, the negative rights argument was articulated most prominently by Herbert Spencer, and it was against him that Durkheim’s criticisms were directed. As we shall see below, Durkheim was an advocate of justice in economic exchanges, and believed that redis- tribution was necessary to ensure justice. He was therefore critical of the free-market argu- ment’s rejection of positive rights. However, this is not what is at issue in the next few para- graphs. Here we will attend to what can be called a sub-argument within the bigger argument about rights. Durkheim was in particular critical of Spencer’s argument that social order can be attained purely on the basis of self-interested exchanges in the marketplace. This argument was first advanced by the Scottish political economist and Enlightenment philosopher, Adam Smith, in his famous book The Wealth of Nations (1776). Philosophers differ in other respects with regard to their justification of the primacy of negative rights (some departing from a utilitarian framework, and others such as Nozick basing their arguments on Locke’s social contract theo- ry, as well as Kant), but Smith’s argument about the possibility of social integration purely on the basis of market exchanges is central to all of them. Any theory that defends a notion of a limited state and an exclusive emphasis on negative rights needs to prove that a setup in which rights are limited in that way is viable and will not create conflict. III Social Order Based Purely on Self-Interested Market Exchanges Smith’s argument was advanced in a context where philosophers had been wondering for some time how social order could be maintained in the new society that was then forming in Europe. Religious wars following upon the Protestant Reformation, the decline of feudal society and later the beginning of the Industrial Revolution all contributed to disruptive social change. Hobbes formulated this question in terms of what later came to be known as the ‘problem of order’: Given that all people are inherently selfish, how will it be possible for us to avoid a state of constant conflict? As is well-known, his answer was that individuals will agree to subordi- nate themselves to a strong sovereign, who will be charged to keep order among them. A more extreme answer was provided some time later by the reactionary Frenchman, Joseph De Maistre. Social order, he said, is guaranteed in the last instance by one man only: the execu- tioner.2 Both of these believed that it is necessary for individuals to offer up their freedom to ensure social order. This was not Smith’s viewpoint. His argument was that neither the The Just Community 109 2 I Berlin ‘The Counter-Enlightenment’ in Against the Current: Essays in the History of Ideas (1980) at 23. 1 1 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E sovereign not the executioner is necessary. Social order can arise spontaneously, if the right institutional setting is provided, from the free actions of individuals in the marketplace. Smith (and Spencer) believed that the ‘invisible hand’ of the market has the remarkable capacity to ensure that the greater good will be served if people pursue their own selfish ends. The argument is as follows: The basis for progress in a society is the increasing division of labour. If a large enough market exists in which individuals can freely exchange their products, the division of labour in a society will grow more complex. People will specialise in making one product only, and will cease to be self-sufficient. This specialisation will both make people more dependent on others and lead to increased productivity and economic growth. Division of labour is also the key to social integration. Market exchanges take place because people need the products produced by others. In a competitive environment, it will be in the enlightened self-interest of sellers not to exploit their customers, because customers can always patronise the competition if they are not satisfied. Market pressures therefore make it possible to regulate the relationships between exchange partners so that conflict does not result from their interaction. In a free market, social order arises, purely unintentionally, from the selfish desires of individuals. It is obvious why this argument is attractive to libertarians. Central direc- tion from the state, or any other form of extraneous regulation, is not necessary to create social order. In fact, they believe it would distort the working of the market and should therefore be avoided.3 Thus the responsibilites of the state to its citizens should be limited to guaranteeing the negative freedoms of individuals. Redistributive actions to ensure positive rights are conse- quently forbidden. IV Durkheim’s Critique The first part of this argument was less contentious for Durkheim. He certainly recognised the capacity of the division of labour to increase productivity. He did, however, have major prob- lems with the next part of this position, which was that the free market, by itself, was able to integrate society and that it should therefore be left unregulated. Durkheim insisted on the opposite: if implemented consistently, free-market policies would lead to conflict and social dis- organisation and destabilise society. It would encourage a radical individualism that elevated the interests of the individual above that of society. This radical individualism, he said, placed no limits on the individual’s desires. As a result, these desires become uncontrollable, which leads to conflict between people as their massive egos clash in search of self-gratification.4 But this does not mean that all kinds of individualism are bad. A more responsible individualism that takes into account social needs was indeed a good thing. Durkheim, like Smith and Spencer, supported individual freedom against the depredations of the sovereign and the executioner. This put him in the liberal camp in terms of the debates of the day. He made it clear that the old basis of social order, which centred around unquestion- ing obedience to church, king and country was no longer viable. People had become emanci- pated from these structures, and this was a good thing; not something to be deplored. What 3 Smith’s book has been somewhat unfairly typecast as an unqualified defence of freemarket capitalism. His book also contains cogent arguments about the need for state interventions in some cases. 4 E Durkheim The Division of Labour in Society (1984) at xxxii; E Durkheim The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (1995) at 427. was needed now, he argued, was new institutions and values with the capacity to gain the respect and support of modern, emancipated, individuals. These institutions will aim to defend individual freedom, even as they guard against the abuse of this freedom. We now move to the specifics of Durkheim’s argument against Spencer. Durkheim claimed that Spencer was wrong in believing that self-interest and the negative rights necessary to pur- sue it could act as the basis for social peace.5 He made the following points: Self-interest is not stable enough to act as the basis for social peace. According to Durkheim, it may be in my interests to cooperate with you today, but then again it may be against my inter- ests to do so tomorrow.6 Durkheim unfortunately did not elaborate on this point, so it is not clear why he thought self-interest should be so inconstant in its effects. It is not difficult to find reasons to support his argument, though. The free market analysed by Smith represents an ide- alised situation that does not appear very often in reality. It assumes a multitude of sellers and buyers, with no single one of them big enough to force his/her terms on the others. In the real world, of course, monopolies and oligopolies are common, entry costs to new competitors high, and arm-twisting (and leg-breaking) rife, so market discipline is absent to a significant extent. In these cases, self-interest leads to exploitation by the powerful. Even the idealised free-mar- ket situation can only account for relationships between buyers and sellers. It does not provide any antidote to conflict, and hard-ball tactics, between sellers, for example. A good example of this was the state of war that existed in the unregulated minibus-taxi industry of South Africa until recently. The free-market argument is particularly problematic in the case of the labour/capital rela- tionship. According to Durkheim, free-market ideologues like to say that, if employers offer salaries that are too low, they will not find workers to fill these positions, because no rational person will work in an occupation if the salary does not match the work involved.7 They there- fore believe that the market forces of supply and demand will, by themselves, ensure that work- ers are compensated at a level equivalent to their productivity, because a shortage of workers will force employers to increase wages. What they forget is that a whole section of the popula- tion cannot abandon their function in this way, since no other is available to them. A worker may very well find him- or herself in such a powerless position. Such a person may be desper- ate to find a job simply to ward off starvation, in which case s/he will take any job on offer regardless of the employment conditions. The weak bargaining position of workers may there- fore render the discipline of market forces on employers inoperative, because they will not expe- rience a shortage in their labour supply that can force them to improve conditions of work. This can lead to great injustices. The negative rights that people are exercising in their contractual relations ‘detach them from one another, and mark out clearly the barriers separating them’.8 This can indeed limit the encroachment of one person upon another, according to Durkheim. But this is not enough to bring about social peace; instead ‘it presumes it’: ‘In fact, for a man to acknowledge that oth- ers have rights… he must have agreed to limit his own. Consequently this mutual limitation was only realisable in a spirit of understanding and mutual harmony’.9 The name Durkheim gave The Just Community 111 5 E Durkheim Professional Ethics and Civic Morals (1957) at 52-53, 71-72; Durkheim The Division of Labour (note 4 above) at 149. 6 Durkheim The Division of Labour (note 4 above) at 152. 7 Durkheim The Division of Labour (note 4 above) at 310. 8 Durkheim The Division of Labour (note 4 above) at 75. 9 Durkheim The Division of Labour (note 4 above) at 76. 1 1 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E for the social cohesion that causes people not to interfere with others, and thus enables their negative rights, was solidarity. Durkheim’s argument here assumes that the argument above about the inconstancy of self-interest is proven. It is not immediately clear that solidarity is the only reason why people would agree to limit their own rights. Enlightened self-interest, for example, can also be a reason, and unless this is excluded as a motivation, his argument is incomplete. But as we have seen, self-interest does indeed not guarantee social order, so this objection does not apply. V Durkheimian and Marxist Critiques of the Free Market Durkheim was one of the first social theorists to question the ability of free markets to integrate society. As is well-known, Marx and Engels before him were very critical of the impact of the divi- sion of labour on the working classes, as well as the conflict produced by capitalist relations of production.10 It should be clear that Durkheim’s analysis of the forced division of labour shows some similarities to Marx’s critique. Durkheim was also sympathetic to some socialist policies, as we shall see later on. Nevertheless, he differed from the Marxists in one important respect.11 Durkheim claimed that the socialisation of the means of production was not, by itself, the solu- tion to such problems. If the selfishness of individuals is not subjected to moral constraint, even socialism would not put an end to conflict. Individual desires will only remain within the capaci- ty of a socialist society to satisfy them if they are controlled by the common morality.12 VI Durkheim and Neo-Institutionalism The belief in the self-regulating market later came to occupy a central position in the successor to the political economy tradition of Adam Smith: neo-classical economics. Recently however, economists in the neo-institutionalist school have become critical of the ability of the market to serve by itself as a guarantor of social peace, and thus of neo-classical economics.13 According to them, markets and contracts can serve to discipline discrete (that is, non-repetitive) transac- tions where there is a choice of alternative suppliers and buyers and the goods exchanged are standardised. However, such transactions form only a small part of the total sum of transac- tions in the economy. For the rest, more elaborate governance structures are necessary. This can either take the form of the vertically-integrated firm (that is the firm buys out the supplier, or starts one up by itself) or the form of relational contracting. Williamson explains the rise of the latter two governance structures with reference to the need to minimise transaction costs.14 Transaction costs arise from two characteristics of exchange. Williamson firstly relaxes the unrealistic neo-classical assumption that the exchange parties both possess perfect information and replaces it with one of bounded rationality. In bounded rationality information is costly to obtain, and actors find it difficult to process even 10 K Marx & F Engels The Communist Manifesto (1848). 11 Durkheim Professional Ethics (note 5 above) at 10-11, 31. 12 Durkheim Professional Ethics (note 5 above) at 10-11. 13 I Macneil ‘Economic Analysis of Contractual Relations’ in P Burrows & CG Veljanovski (eds) The Economic Approach to Law (1981) 61; OE Williamson ‘Contract Analysis: The Transaction Cost Approach’ in P Burrows & CG Veljanovski (eds) The Economic Approach to Law (1981) 39. 14 Williamson ‘Contract Analysis’ (note 13 above) at 45-46. the little information that they have. This creates a need to economise on the time and effort involved in decision-making. In addition, he assumes that opportunism is a reality in exchanges. This implies that actors are often tempted to hide their real intentions to others, and therefore profit by deceit. The costs resulting from the gathering and processing of information, as well as the safeguards against opportunism, are known as transaction costs. In relational contracting, the buyers and sellers build up a long-term relationship. Here, informal norms that regulate their exchanges develop over time between buyer and seller. In addition, a feeling of solidarity develops between the partners. This builds up trust between them. These characteristics of relational contracting allow actors to reduce their transaction costs. Long-term relationships simplify decision-making, and trust reduces the need to guard against opportunism. As a result, the partners are prepared to limit their immediate self-inter- est for the sake of the relationship. Their attitude tends to become more one of enlightened self- interest, taking the longer view. They realise that their relationship allows them to benefit more as a group than would otherwise have been possible if they had acted as individuals only. Although I am not aware of any direct line of influence from Durkheim to the new institu- tionalists, it should be clear that there are important similarities between Durkheim’s work and theirs. However, there are also important differences. Despite their deviations from neo-classi- cal economics, Williamson and others in this tradition still depart from a micro-perspective, taking the individual as their point of departure. They also share an economising perspective with neo-classical economics. Both of these points of departure are foreign to Durkheim. Moral behaviour is not just a means to an end for Durkheim, as it is for the neo-institutionalists, it is an important end in itself: ‘It is not merely a matter of increasing the exchanges of goods and services, but of seeing that they are done by rules that are more just; it is not simply that every- one should have access to rich supplies of food and drink.15 Rather, it is that each one should be treated as he deserves, each be freed from an unjust and humiliating tutelage, and that, in holding to his fellows and his group, a man should not sacrifice his individuality.’ Durkheim finally was resolutely a macro-theorist. For him society was a reality in its own right that had a major impact on the individual, as we shall see below. VII Durkheim’s Ideal Typical Picture of Social Development In the light of the foregoing, it is not surprising that Durkheim thought that contemporary European societies exhibited numerous symptoms of social disintegration. Industrialisation caused the disintegration of the feudal societies of earlier times. In their place, a new society was coming into being, with industrial capitalism as its mode of production and individual free- dom as its dominant ideology. Opinions varied about the viability, and desirability, of this new world, which later came to be known as ‘modernity’. For Durkheim this new world was not viable in its then current form. The market was subject to few controls. Old forms of commu- nity were eroded by capitalism and new forms were not instituted. The disorganisation he observed was precisely what would follow from the absence of regulation of economic exchanges, and the failure to install solidarity and new forms of sociability between people. This leads to the social problems of what he called egoism and anomie. In order to understand why these problems come to the fore, we need to briefly consider The Just Community 113 15 Durkheim Professional Ethics (note 5 above) at 71-72. 1 1 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E Durkheim’s exposition of the role of increasing division of labour and decreasing collective con- sciousness in the rise of modern societies. In his book Division of Labour in Society Durkheim worked out an ideal typical scheme of social development. He defined the problem he was going to study as follows: ‘How does it come about that the individual, whilst becoming more autonomous, depends ever more closely upon society?’.16 This then was Durkheim’s vision of social development: There is an historical trend towards increasing individualism. Under ideal circumstances this trend does not produce a lack of social cohesion, and it was the intention of his book to show why this was possible. Because this ideal line of development was not fol- lowed, the extremes of egoism and anomie mentioned above, resulted. Armed with the concepts developed here, we will return later on to the discussion of what in his view went wrong. Durkheim believed that the division of labour is very simple in primitive societies. In a hunter and gatherer type of society, men are the hunters and women the childminders and gatherers. Here the division of labour is largely based on gender, with some distinctions made on the basis of age. As societies develop the division of labour becomes more complex. In the stage of set- tled agriculture there are occupations such as craftsmen, priests, soldiers, herdsmen and farm- ers. Industrialisation, of course, has an enormous impact on the division of labour. Initially, hundreds but later thousands of new occupations are created as a result of industrialisation. The simple division of labour of primitive societies, where people have similar occupations, is associated with similarities in the feelings, values and beliefs of people. They thus share a strong, collective consciousness. The French term used by Durkheim is conscience collective, which suggests similarities in both cognitive and moral beliefs.17 Durkheim (and his English translators) had a number of names for the collective conscience, which gives an idea of what he meant by it. Besides ‘collective consciousness’, it is alternatively called civic morals, public opinion, common morality or collective representations. The common morality is the basis of what Durkheim calls mechanical solidarity. People feel connected to their neighbours because they are all alike. Durkheim believed that the higher ranges of every person’s consciousness can be divided into two parts: an individual (or unique) part, not shared with other people, and a collective part that consists of the ideas and beliefs similar to other people.18 Mechanical solidarity can only be strong if the second part, that is, the ideas and beliefs common to people, occupy a larger part in each of our minds than the unique part.19 It follows from this that the individual per- sonality, understood as a reasoning and moral being, cannot exist if the collective consciousness occupies our minds completely. In other words, the decline of the collective consciousness is a precondition for the rise of the individual personality.20 This is what happens when the division of labour becomes more complex. More variety creeps into people’s ideas, and this leads to the erosion of the collective consciousness. Like the division of labour, the collective consciousness becomes more fragmented.21 Because people now have such diverse experiences in the world of work due to the division of labour, ideas and 16 Durkheim The Division of Labour (note 4 above) at xxx. 17 Durkheim The Elementary Forms (note 4 above) at 214; A Giddens Studies in Social and Political Theory (1977). 18 Durkheim The Division of Labour (note 4 above) at 61. 19 Durkheim The Division of Labour (note 4 above) at 84. 20 Durkheim The Division of Labour (note 4 above) at 142; D Gelderblom Morality, Individual and Society: Emile Durkheim (2004). 21 Durkheim The Division of Labour (note 4 above) at 172. beliefs are no longer shared. In other words, the collective consciousness divides up into parts, each part regulating a particular occupation. The impact of the division of labour on the collective consciousness indicates the link that Durkheim posited between social organisation and belief systems. A small-scale intimate soci- ety produces intensely-held common beliefs, and a large-scale differentiated society produces more variety in and less commitment to common values. The rising division of labour and the declining collective consciousness can, if conditions are right, produce a new kind of solidarity, called organic solidarity. The conditions Durkheim had in mind was the following: division of labour, morality and legal regulation. It should be appar- ent that Durkheim thought that these conditions were not yet in place. Durkheim believed that Spencer and Smith were right to give the division of labour a role in the integration of society, but were wrong about the mechanism by which it would do so.22 The division of labour leads to social harmony, not because it co-ordinates interests, but because it creates solidarity. Because we each specialise in producing only one product (or part thereof) or service, house- holds are no longer self-sufficient. The division of labour therefore makes us dependent on other people to survive. When we become aware of this mutual dependence, we develop a lik- ing for others, as well as a willingness to submit our interests to social regulation. Peaceful and orderly exchanges between individuals depend on these feelings. Durkheim made it very clear that the interdependence created by the division of labour was not enough to serve as the basis of solidarity, however.23 The new occupations created by the division of labour needed to be regulated to make sure that conflict does not arise. The first form of social regulation was moral. As Durkheim put it: ‘A state of order or peace among men cannot follow of itself from any entirely material causes, from any blind mecha- nism, however scientific it may be. It is a moral task’.24 The ‘blind mechanism’ that Durkheim was referring to here was obviously the invisible hand of the market. Moral regulation is nec- essary to prevent ‘the law of the strongest from being applied too brutally in industrial and commercial relationships’.25 It imposes control over the selfish impulses of individuals. It also leads to just outcomes in the marketplace, which makes the less privileged more inclined to accept the outcomes of economic exchanges. Durkheim believed that for every occupation a professional morality was necessary, along the lines of the ethical standards that apply to advocates. The fact that this was absent in the case of most other occupations was a matter of concern to Durkheim.26 Professional ethics would not arise in a social vacuum, however, and consequently Durkheim argued that it was necessary to organise all the occupations into occupational groups.27 These groups would pro- vide the facilitating context that could induce such moralities, as we shall see later. Professional moralities were guided by a broader social morality, the collective conscience. In modern societies this common morality revolved around what he called the ‘cult of the indi- vidual’.28 This cult comes to prominence in the modern world because this kind of society The Just Community 115 22 Durkheim The Division of Labour (note 4 above) at 333. 23 Durkheim The Division of Labour (note 4 above) at 172-173, 301. 24 Durkheim Professional Ethics (note 5 above) at 12. 25 Durkheim The Division of Labour (note 4 above) at xxxix. 26 Durkheim Professional Ethics (note 5 above) at 30; Durkheim The Division of Labour (note 4 above) at 174. 27 Durkheim Professional Ethics (note 5 above) at 7-12. 28 Durkheim Professional Ethics (note 5 above) at 56, 69-70; Durkheim The Division of Labour (note 4 above) at 122. 1 1 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E accords the individual a sacred status: ‘We carry on the worship of the dignity of the human person…it is indeed a common faith’.29 As traditional religion loses its credibility the cult of the individual grows to take its place. Durkheim’s recourse to the common morality seems somewhat paradoxical on the surface, because his analysis has also demonstrated that it weakens as a result of division of labour. It also makes mechanical and organic solidarity less distinct. At least part of the solution to this paradox is that it now serves only as a backup to the professional morality: it only regulates broader conflicts in society across occupational lines. Perhaps Durkheim also sensed a problem here. Later in his life he investigated how religious (and secular) rituals could strengthen the common beliefs of communities. It thus seems as if Durkheim later on tried to look for mech- anisms by which common beliefs could be reinvigorated. Another problem is the vagueness about which of the two factors are independent and which dependent variables: social organi- sation or beliefs? Division of labour (social organisation) affects beliefs, but beliefs are neces- sary to forestall social disorganisation in the form of conflict, and so on. There is in principle no objection if both affect each other, but more clarity about the logic involved here would have been welcome. This is so especially in the light of his inclination, noted by Lukes, toward cir- cular argumentation.30 Moral ideas find expression in the legal system, which is the second form of regulation. It is necessary for contracts to be embedded in a legal framework that can clarify the many grey areas that can arise when two individuals enter into a contract. A contract therefore implies duties that go beyond those that individuals have agreed upon.31 VIII The Reality of Social Disintegration We have now finished with the ideal picture; the way development should have happened according to Durkheim. We now need to find out what went wrong to produce the egoism and anomie that he perceived around him at the time. Egoism occurs when people are too self-centred.32 Durkheim linked this excessive individu- alism to a decline in the levels of social integration. If social bonds weaken, people do not build up strong associations with groups; that is, they no longer feel part of a group. As a result, the group ceases to be an important anchor for individuals, and they become isolated and feel they lack meaning in life. Pre-industrial societies showed higher levels of social integration than modern societies, according to Durkheim. The ways in which they manufactured those high levels of integration are no longer viable, however, and alternatives have to be found.33 They created high levels of integration by restricting individual initiative in unacceptable ways, or through institutions that no longer exist in their original form. For example, religious belief systems were protected against doubt by restrictions on free thinking, and this ensured the continued viability of reli- gious groups as sources of social contact for individuals.34 However, the restrictions placed by 29 Durkheim The Division of Labour (note 4 above) at 122. 30 S Lukes Émile Durkheim. His Life and Work: A Historical and Critical Study (1975) at 31. 31 Durkheim The Division of Labour (note 4 above) at 159. 32 E Durkheim Suicide. A Study in Sociology (1952) at 209. 33 Durkheim Suicide (note 32 above) at 375. 34 Durkheim Suicide (note 32 above) at 374. religion on free thinking offends modern value systems. Unlike in the past, people no longer unquestioningly accept the authority of religion, and will not allow religious bodies to prescribe to them how they must think. Another source of integration was the pre-industrial family. According to Durkheim, this family type was large and close-knit and provided many oppor- tunities for social contact. Modern families are much smaller and isolated from communal con- tact however, and can no longer play the integrating role they used to.35 Anomie is the result of the frustration, and consequent suffering, of people when their appetites outrun their ability to satisfy them. Anomie is related to egoism, as Durkheim remarks, because it also results from ‘society’s insufficient presence in individuals’.36 Despite this similarity, egoism and anomie differ with regard to the part of society in which this lack is experienced. Egoism derives from the world of morality and the intellect, and produces a lack of meaning and purpose in life. Anomie, by contrast, is located in the world of the economy. Anomie is endemic in modern society. According to Durkheim, this is because human needs have grown out of all proportion.37 Apart from some physical needs such as food, where phys- iological processes create a feeling of satiation once they have been met, human needs such as the need for luxury or money are, in principle, insatiable. Needs that can never be satisfied cause the individual to chase after infinity. It means being placed on a treadmill, running ever faster after a goal that can never be met. Needs have grown so much in modern societies because they are no longer limited, as before, by forces such as religion which taught people to be satisfied with their station in life. The market has also grown to such an extent that it has reached global proportions. Like Marx, Durkheim anticipated the globalizing tendency of the capitalist market.38 The development of the global market was associated with the rise of another phenomenon, which Durkheim did not foresee: the advertising industry. This industry is dedicated to the manufacturing of new needs and increases the extent to which people’s desires outrun their ability to satisfy them. IX Durkheim’s Solutions This is the set of circumstances that has made anomie endemic in modern societies. To solve this problem, people need to accept their desires being limited for the greater good. Morality is the only force with the capacity to ensure this agreement, according to Durkheim.39 It would do so as follows: In a just society there would be a broad consensus on the level of remunera- tion that each occupation in society deserves. For every occupation, there will be a generally accepted maximum beyond which it is regarded as unrealistic, and immoral, to strive. This social determination of acceptable living standards for each occupation was not very exact.40 It gives a range within which each individual can set his or her expectations for life, with the result that people have some scope for improving their circumstances within these limits. The important thing, though, is that it sets a maximum, and thus ensures that individuals do not become frustrated as a result of their inability to fulfil their unlimited desires. The Just Community 117 35 Durkheim Suicide (note 32 above) at 377. 36 Durkheim Suicide (note 32 above) at 258. 37 Durkheim Suicide (note 32 above) at 247. 38 Durkheim Suicide (note 32 above) at 255-256. 39 Durkheim Suicide (note 32 above) at 248-249. 40 Durkheim Suicide (note 32 above) at 250. 1 1 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E Durkheim’s belief that people will allow their desires to be limited in this way is open to criti- cism. People do indeed accept their station in life to a remarkable degree. They tend to limit their expectations of life to within the horizons of what they perceive to be the possible. But there is also a constant conflict over the distribution of resources in modern societies, which suggests that this self-imposed limitation only goes so far. In Durkheim’s defence one can say that he did not believe that the modern societies he analysed actually exhibited such consensus: only in a just society will such a consensus exist. In fact, this is the whole point of his analysis of anomie: regulatory structures have not yet developed, thus predisposing modern societies to anomie. People will not accept that others deserve to be remunerated better than they if the lat- ter started out with unfair advantages in life. Until such time, conflict over the distribution of resources will indeed be rife. A just distribution of resources is therefore a precondition for solv- ing anomie. This raises the question of what Durkheim meant by ‘just’. What social arrangements need to be in place for just outcomes to be produced in the marketplace? In short, Durkheim believed that only distributional outcomes that resulted from a situation where everybody had an equal chance to perform, were just. Only those social arrangements that allow people to rise to positions based purely on their merits, and where the accident of birth played no role whatsoever in their career path, thus qualified.41 This means that any mechanism by which the privileged could transmit their privileged position to their children had to be eliminated. Durkheim therefore made a plea for inherited wealth to be abolished.42 Inherited wealth gave those lucky enough to have acquired it an unfair advantage in life’s race. The same applies to factors such as unequal access to educa- tion. If there are obstacles placed in the way of individuals’ realising their talents, such as inherit- ed poverty, or a lack of education, the division of labour is forced and equality of opportunity can- not be realised.43 Durkheim’s plea was thus for a system of meritocracy. But this still leaves an important objection. What is so compelling about meritocracy that people will generally accept it as the guiding distribution principle? It is only one out of a num- ber of theories of justice. There are also different versions of the meritocratic principle.44 Some theorists believe that the only social arrangements necessary for equality of opportunity to be realised is the absence of legal obstacles (such as job discrimination) to individual advancement. Others are more demanding with regard to the criteria that need to be in place for it to be realised. This more radical version of meritocracy also prescribes that people need to be given the same resources to perform. It should be clear that Durkheim falls in the latter category. Even if we grant Durkheim that the notion of meritocracy has powerful resonance in modern socie- ty, why should people necessarily accept his version of the principle rather than others? Durkheim did have an answer to this objection, but it is not very convincing. As we said above, he postulated a close correlation between the type of social organisation and the kind of belief systems that will be found in a society. Given that the individual occupies such an impor- tant place in modern society, only philosophies that elevated the individual to a high status and that wanted to give each an equal chance would be viable, he believed. Although there certain- ly is some truth to this belief, the picture is much more complex than this, as the variety in polit- ical philosophies competing for acceptance in modern societies demonstrates. 41 Durkheim Suicide (note 32 above) at 251. 42 Durkheim Suicide (note 32 above) at 251; Durkheim The Division of Labour (note 4 above) at 313-314. 43 Durkheim The Division of Labour (note 4 above) at 314. 44 Christman Social and Political Philosophy (note 1 above) at 62-63. A further objection to Durkheim’s theory is that he does not provide a criterium to distinguish a forced consensus from a genuine one. What is called ‘public opinion’ often reflects the views of powerful, and wealthy, people in society rather than the views of ordinary people. It is the pow- erful and the wealthy who own and control newspapers and television stations, not the latter. Nevertheless, Durkheim’s belief that individual desires need to be constrained has some res- onance if we look at the ecological imperatives faced by late modern societies. It is doubtful that the planet has the capacity to absorb the damage that will be caused to its ecosystems if every- body consumed at the level of the average American. Besides the notion of justice, Durkheim also foresaw a role for two social structures in his solution to egoism and anomie. These are the professional group and the state. They will respectively nurture the professional ethics and the common morality necessary to regulate eco- nomic life. The professional group will also form the vehicle by which the close community bonds of yore will be recreated. With the advent of the division of labour, morality starts to differentiate between the different occupations, as we have seen above. But morality remains very weakly developed and feebly en- forced if there isn’t a group that is dedicated to promoting it. The stronger the group cohesion, the more numerous and binding the moral rules will be. Occupational groups are, according to Durkheim, particularly suited to fulfill this task. Durkheim’s idea was that each trade or occupa- tion should constitute itself into a professional group with regulatory powers. All the people that work in the construction industry, for example, employers and employees alike, should come to- gether on a national basis in a professional group that is dedicated to that industry.45 In this group, decisions will be made about the appropriate regulations governing the relationships between employer and employee, between competitors, and between contractors and their clients.46 Durkheim hoped that such a group would, over time, start taking on an almost familial char- acter.47 People will find their most important social bonds in this group. Durkheim hoped that these groups would cause ‘the present cold moral temperature’ of the world of work to become warmer.48 This group would also look after the welfare of individuals, providing services such as unemployment insurance and pensions.49 If a breadwinner falls ill for example, this group will support his or her dependents. However, professional groups could not regulate the economy on their own. Some agency is necessary to guide the relationships between the different spheres of work. Each profession would naturally attempt to promote the interests of their own members, sometimes at the expense of the interests of others. This is where the state comes in, according to Durkheim.50 It was the only agency with a broad enough view to look after the interests of society as a whole, and thus to guard against abuses committed by sectional interests. It has to formulate and administer the general laws that regulate economic life. Professional groups, for their part, had to keep the state in check.51 In their absence, the state may become totalitarian, and com- pletely stifle individual freedom. The Just Community 119 45 Durkheim Professional Ethics (note 5 above) at 37. 46 Durkheim Professional Ethics (note 5 above) at 9. 47 Durkheim Professional Ethics (note 5 above) at 21. 48 Durkheim Suicide (note 32 above) at 381. 49 Durkheim Suicide (note 32 above) at 380. 50 Durkheim Suicide (note 32 above) at 374; Durkheim Professional Ethics (note 5 above) at 62; Durkheim The Division of Labour (note 4 above) at li, liv. 51 Durkheim Suicide (note 32 above) at 380; Durkheim Professional Ethics (note 5 above) at 63; Durkheim The Division of Labour (note 4 above) at liv. 1 2 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E This balance of opposing forces was essential for individual freedom to be realised, according to Durkheim. The state is necessary to free individuals from the ‘collective particularisms’ of secondary groups.52 These can take the form of professional groups, local communities, reli- gious groups or clans. Although they provide communal bonds and opportunities for sociabil- ity to the individual, these groups can also, because of their cohesiveness, repress individuality if they are not held in check. Due to the important role of the state in this regard, it is thus not true to claim that a small state is necessary for individual freedom, as free-market liberals claim, according to Durkheim.53 In fact, the opposite is the case, provided that a strong civic life exists to keep the state in check. X Why the Invisible Hand of the Market is not Good Enough: A Summary It is perhaps now time to draw the different strands of Durkheim’s complex argument against free market liberalism together. The free market does not have the capacity to create sponta- neous social order out of the economic exchanges of selfish individual egos. It will, instead, pro- duce conflict and social disorganisation. It assumes, for its functioning, social cohesion, but destroys such cohesion wherever it exists. This because it destroys previous forms of commu- nity, and does not replace them with anything new. It is also because it produces market out- comes that are clearly unjust, and that cannot receive popular legitimacy. Its end result is enor- mous individual egos with no conception of the common good. To solve this problem, new forms of community are necessary that are more viable in the light of the division of labour. To make sure that these forms of community do not repeat the mistake of the old and repress individuality completely, the state is necessary to protect, and nurture individual freedoms. The communal groups are likewise needed to keep the state in check. These forms of social organisation should also produce the professional and common moralities needed to provide social cohesion in modernity. Durkheim’s critique of ‘atomistic’ liberalism and his emphasis on the need for communal bonds to maintain social cohesion have clear similarities with the current proponents of communitarian- ism such as Alasdair MacIntyre. He differs from them however with regard to his choice of com- munity to provide these communal bonds: the professional group. His choice of this group, and his discourse on the need for the state to watch over communal groups to ensure that they do not repress individuality, demonstrates his sophistication. He thus anticipated the criticism of liberals like Kymlicka who pointed to the repressive tendencies of these groups. Durkheim can also be crit- icised however for his somewhat optimistic belief in the capacity of a common morality to contain the conflict of interests between the employer and employee constituents of the professional groups. XI The Social Construction of the Moral Subject We can now move on to another part of Durkheim’s communitarian critique of liberalism: its conception of the subject. The notion of a free human subject of knowledge forms the basis for 52 Durkheim Professional Ethics (note 5 above) at 61-62. 53 Durkheim Professional Ethics (note 5 above) at 57. the defence of human rights in many currents of human rights discourse.54 It is derived essen- tially from the work of the 18th century German philosopher, Immanuel Kant. For Kant knowl- edge is only possible on condition that a subject of such knowledge exists. Knowledge of the world cannot only be built upon the manifold impressions received from the senses. The sense impressions have to be constituted into meaningful perceptions, otherwise they will remain essentially chaotic. This is done by what Kant called the intuitions of space and time, and the categories of understanding such as cause, number, modality, and so on. The intuitions and cat- egories are the basis of the knowing subject. Because they are a precondition for observation they cannot themselves be observed. This is why Kant called them a priori. The subject of knowledge therefore stands observation; it is the ground of observation but never itself the object of observation. The subject, as Kant defined it, is universal. All individual subjects with the capacity for knowledge have these attributes. This subject is also the precondition for our ability to act morally. Because it is not consti- tuted by observations of external (the world outside us) or internal (our own feelings and desires) objects, it completely escapes determination by them. It is therefore essentially free of outside conditioning. For Kant our actions can only be truly moral if they are based on a free exercise of our will, and not the result of conditioning by other forces. The existence of free will is the starting point of Kant’s ethics. Society should be ordered in such a way that maximum scope is offered to individuals to freely exercise their will. In addition, my interaction with oth- ers must always take into account that they also possess a free will, just like me. I must there- fore treat other people as ends in themselves and not as means to my own ends. Ethical rules should furthermore be universal: I can only act in a particular way if I also accept that the con- sequences will be acceptable if everybody else acts in that way. Durkheim agreed with Kant’s ethics, as well has his views on the need for a priori categories of understanding to make sense of observation. However, he differed from him in one impor- tant respect: the moral subject is a social construction, and not innate. From this it follows that the subject can never be as autonomous as Kant thought s/he should be. Individual autonomy must always be balanced by individual dependency on society. In the next few paragraphs we will pursue Durkheim’s differences with Kant. In tune with his notion that the collective con- sciousness contains both a cognitive and a moral dimension, he gives attention to both aspects in Kant’s thought. To begin with the subject of knowledge: According to Durkheim, proponents of the view that the categories are innate, such as Kant, have the problem of explaining where they come from.55 But the alternative view, that the categories must have come from experience, was not acceptable either. This view implies that every individual subconsciously learns to make sense of his/her experience by slowly developing these categories over time. This empiricist approach, Durkheim argued, is no solution to the problem. The categories are prior to expe- rience and they cannot be derived from experience. If this is done, they lose their universali- ty and necessity. To overcome this dilemma, Durkheim offered a new solution. In his view, the categories are social in origin.56 They are collective representations that have developed over many genera- tions and that therefore contain the accumulated wisdom of innumerable numbers of individu- als. Because they have been tested in experience over such a long time, they have acquired a The Just Community 121 54 MJ Sandel Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (1998). 55 Durkheim The Elementary Forms (note 4 above) at 13-14. 56 Durkheim The Elementary Forms (note 4 above) at 15. 1 2 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E degree of impersonality and objectivity and can therefore serve as a ground for our experi- ence.57 Because of the social derivation of knowledge, it changes as social organisation changes. Initially it is very much culture-bound. Since the beginning of the modern world, a new kind of society has arisen, however, which Durkheim called international life, or international society.58 This is Durkheim’s version of globalization theory. Because society now becomes more univer- sal, knowledge has to become more universal as well. As a result it jettisons its particularistic attachments, and this allows us to comes much closer to universal truths. In this case, then, the categories will indeed be universal, like Kant said, but that universality is not due to an innate characteristic of the human subject. It is rather the product of social development. Durkheim makes much the same argument with regard to the moral subject: ‘What lies at the basis of individual right is not the notion of the individual as he is, but the way society puts the right into practice, looks upon it and appraises it…The reason why he has more or fewer rights, certain rights and not others, is not that he is constituted in a particular way; it is because society attributes this or that importance to him’.59 An indication of this is the fact that the rights of individuals are ‘in a state of evolution’.60 Durkheim is further convinced that the autonomy that Kant ascribes to humans cannot ever be absolute.61 Human autonomy always has to be counterbalanced by the real dependency of ourselves upon society. Durkheim’s emphasis on individual autonomy as well as dependency has to be seen in the light of his project to, on the one hand, combat a radical individualism, that is an individual- ism that elevated the interests of the individual above that of society, and to find space for indi- vidual freedom on the other. His argument for our dependency on society was as follows: We are dependent upon society, firstly, for our own survival.62 With the rise of the division of labour, other people become the source of the food we eat and all the products we consume. Society is secondly also a source of social recognition and of companionship. We furthermore owe our culture to society: ‘We speak a language we did not create; we use instruments we did not invent; we claim rights we did not establish; each generation inherits a treasury of knowl- edge that it did not itself amass, and so on. We owe these varied benefits of civilization to soci- ety, and although in general we do not see where they come from, we know at least that they are not of our own making.’63 Society can finally uplift and strengthen us. In communal gath- erings, crowd psychology can lead to great outpourings of emotion which can leave people feel- ing transformed and renewed.64 To make sense of Durkheim’s position, we have to return to his vision of social development outlined above. He viewed human personalities as having a double nature: it consists of a col- lective and an individual part. The individual person only comes into existence when the col- lective conscience erodes enough so that it no longer rests so heavily on individual personali- ties. This is the result of the development of the division of labour. Predictably, Durkheim was heavily criticized for this notion of a collective consciousness and 57 Durkheim The Elementary Forms (note 4 above) at 437. 58 Durkheim The Elementary Forms (note 4 above) at 446. 59 Durkheim Professional Ethics (note 5 above) at 67; Durkheim The Division of Labour (note 4 above) at 335. 60 Durkheim Professional Ethics (note 5 above) at 68. 61 Durkheim Professional Ethics (note 5 above) at 68. 62 Durkheim The Elementary Forms (note 4 above) at 208. 63 Durkheim The Elementary Forms (note 4 above) at 214. 64 Durkheim The Elementary Forms (note 4 above) at 211-212. his attendant belief in the reality of society as a force above individuals. Durkheim believed that society was a reality in its own right, separate from the individuals constituting it, even though it consisted of nothing but them in their combination. Because it questions dearly-held assump- tions about the autonomy of individuals, this idea has encountered a lot of resistance. Especially the liberal tradition with its emphasis on the rights of individuals has had great difficulty accommodating it. Even the great John Rawls objected to notions that ‘society is an organic whole with a life of its own distinct from and superior to that of all its members in their rela- tions with one another’.65 A common reaction seems to be that the belief in a separate social reality contains illegitimate metaphysical assumptions, but it is really nothing of the sort. Durkheim’s notion of social reality is based on the very straightforward principle of emergent systemic properties. The argument is as follows: society is a complex system. It comes into being when individuals are combined in an organised way.66 The combination produces something new, something that is different from the parts.67 Society is therefore an emergent property of the complex organisa- tion of individuals, to put it in the language of systems theory. The way society arises from the organisation of its parts is no different from the way life arises from the properties of organic mol- ecules in their combination, or the way consciousness arises from the complex organisation of the brain for that matter.68 The materialist objection that consciousness must be an illusion because there is nothing in the brain but physical matter, is as silly as the idea that society must be an illu- sion because there is nothing in society but individual people. Both are emergent properties of complex systems. Understood in this way, it is difficult to see that the notion that society is a sep- arate reality makes ontological assumptions any different from those implied by Kant’s moral sub- ject, or the freely choosing individuals so dear to neo-classical economics. What evidence do we have that society is a reality in its own right? Well, Durkheim says, we become aware of the independent existence of society through the effects it has upon us.69 One of these is the constraint imposed by social norms.70 According to Durkheim, we are not, in the normal conduct of our lives, aware that our actions are constrained.71 As he puts it somewhere, we are no more aware of the weight of society than we are aware of the weight of the atmos- phere pressing upon us. It is only when we transgress social expectations that we become aware of these constraints. The obvious case of this is the penalties that await us if we break the law. But there exist other, less obvious ways, of controlling our behaviour in the form of our fear of being rejected by our peers. We also see the effects of society in the way social intercourse can transform individuals. During rituals, people lose their individuality to some extent, and become part of a bigger whole. They emerge from these experiences transformed and reinvigorated. This experience is especially common during times of collective ferment, such as political uprisings. Describing the situation during the French Revolution, Durkheim says: ‘We see the most mediocre or harmless bourgeois transformed by the general exaltation into a hero or an executioner’.72 But this trans- The Just Community 123 65 Sandel Liberalism (note 54 above) at 53. 66 E Durkheim The Rules of Sociological Method and Selected Texts on Sociology and its Method (1982) at 129. 67 Durkheim The Rules of Sociological Method (note 66 above) at 39, 45. 68 Durkheim The Rules of Sociological Method (note 66 above) at 43. 69 Durkheim The Rules of Sociological Method (note 66 above) at 43-51. 70 Durkheim The Rules of Sociological Method (note 66 above) at 51. 71 Durkheim The Rules of Sociological Method (note 66 above) at 51. 72 Durkheim The Elementary Forms (note 4 above) at 212. 1 2 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E formative effect is not only restricted to exceptional circumstances. Religious rituals, or civic celebrations, can have such an effect on a regular basis. Society is mostly made up of representations, and it therefore ‘ideal’ in that sense. These rep- resentations have a logic of their own, separate from individual representations. Durkheim’s vision of collective representations is similar to the notion of ‘culture’, as it has been developed by anthropologists. Language, and belief systems, and ‘discourses’, are all collective represen- tations in Durkheim’s sense. They all have a certain autonomy from individual conceptions of them, and they all have their own logic, or ‘conditions of existence’. Durkheim’s emphasis on the reality of the social, and its impact on individuals, finds a lot of resonance in the recent communitarian critiques of liberalism. Sandel’s analysis of three differ- ent views of community provides a very useful space to parachute Durkheim into this debate.73 John Rawls’s distinction between two different kinds of community forms the first two of his three categories. Because he puts it so well, I will quote him at length:74 …Of the two accounts of community Rawls presents, both are individualistic, although the way they are individualistic differs in each case. The instrumental account is individualistic in that the subjects of co-operation are assumed to be gov- erned by self-interested motivations alone, and the good of the community consists solely in the advantages individuals derive from co-operating in pursuit of their ego- istic ends. Rawls’s account is individualistic in the sense of assuming the antecedent individuation of the subjects of co-operation, whose actual motivations may include benevolent aims as well as selfish ones… The first sense of community is the one that results from the free actions of individuals in the marketplace, and is the one Durkheim criticised at length. Rawls’s sense of community denies the subject any supra-individual or intersubjective aspects, and is bound to his rejection of the notion of an independent social reality. This is why it assumes the antecedent individuation of subjects. It does, however, recognise that subjects may be motivated by more than self-interest. In this respect, Rawls signals his rejection of a long tradition in social analysis (neo-classical economics, rational choice theory in sociology) which uses individuals’ quest for maximum self- gratification as their main, if not only, explanatory variable. It also signals his rejection of the atomistic, libertarian politics that follows from it. In Rawls’s view, subjects do not only have egoistic motivations, but can also be more altruistic in their intentions. Sandel argues that even Rawls’s ‘sentimental’ view of community is deficient in its concep- tualization of the relationship between the individual and the social: …On this strong view, to say the members of a society are bound by a sense of com- munity is not simply to say that a great many of them profess communitarian senti- ments and pursue communitarian aims, but that they conceive of their identity – the subject and not just the object of their feelings and aspirations – as defined to some extent by the community of which they are a part… .75 Sandel believes that Rawls’s conceptions of distributive justice can only be defended on the basis 73 Sandel Liberalism (note 54 above) at 147-154. 74 Sandel Liberalism (note 54 above) at 148-149. 75 Sandel Liberalism (note 54 above) at 150. of such a ‘constitutive’ view of community, even though Rawls denies the viability of such a view. Because it rests on ‘antecedently individuated’ individuals, Rawls’s view of community is also impoverished. I once again quote at length: …Where “collective” assets imply endowments once separately held, now ceded to society as a whole, “common” assets do not necessarily; they need not logically pre- suppose a prior individuation. And while “reciprocity” implies a principle of exchange and hence a plurality of agents, the notion of “sharing” may suggest a sol- idarity such that no exchange need be involved, as in sharing a joke, or an aspira- tion, or an understanding. And while “association” and “co-operation” typically presuppose the antecedent plurality of those who join together to associate or co- operate, “community” and “participation” may describe a form of life in which the members find themselves commonly situated “to begin with”, their commonality consisting less in relationships they have entered than in attachments they have found… .76 Sandel believes that the constitutive view of community, which he supports, would choose the latter term in this series of oppositions. Sandel’s subject has an individual and a social part, and in this respect it is similar to Durkheim’s view of the subject. His criticisms of Rawls are also similar to the criticisms that one can imagine Durkheim would make. But there is an important difference, and this suggests a limitation to Durkheim’s theory (and in fact to all social con- structionist accounts of the subject that Durkheim has, directly and indirectly, inspired many years later). Sandel’s subject also has an, albeit limited, capacity for self-reflexivity, both indi- vidually and communally.77 It can, alone and in conversation with friends, gain some self- knowledge by distancing itself from its preferences and beliefs. However, the self that I discov- er in this way is always ready made, and the distancing only relative. It is never something that I, as a free agent, using the will, can create anew. This self-knowledge is therefore necessarily situated, and thus limited, but important nevertheless. Through it, the subject has some capac- ity to subject the values of the surrounding community to critical reflection.78 Notions of jus- tice and the good are therefore never simply the product of ‘ethnocentrism’, as in Rorty’s ‘we do not do that around here’, but also demands the capacity to criticize community values.79 This is why Sandel feels somewhat uncomfortable with the communitarian label he has acquired.80 It is of course also the case that he isn’t completely in Kymlicka’s camp either, since the latter completely overestimates the subject’s insight into itself. Durkheim believes that subjects attain some level of distance from communal values as a result of the destruction of pre-industrial communities. They are therefore not completely taken up by the social any more. But this process of individuation seems to rest completely upon social forces, and entails little, if any, activity of self-reflection by the individual. This ties in with another problem with Durkheim’s view of the subject: the lack of agency he ascribes to it. This problem has received extensive attention in the so-called agency-structure debate in sociology, among others by the realist philosopher Roy Bhaskar. Bhaskar agrees with The Just Community 125 76 Sandel Liberalism (note 54 above) at 150. 77 Sandel Liberalism (note 54 above) at 179-181. 78 Sandel Liberalism (note 54 above) at xi. 79 W Kymlicka Liberalism, Community and Culture (1989) at 66. 80 Sandel Liberalism (note 54 above) at xi. 1 2 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E Durkheim’s proof for the existence of society as a real entity (against methodological individu- alism) on the basis of its effects on individuals, and uses it as part of his own argument for the reality of society.81 He criticizes Durkheim however because he had a reified conception of the social as existing separate from the intentional activity of people. Bhaskar summarises his own model of the social as follows: Men do not create society. For it always pre-exists them. Rather it is an ensemble of structures, practices and conventions that individuals reproduce or transform, but which would not exist unless they did so. Society does not exist independently of conscious human activity (the error of reification). But it is not the product of the lat- ter (the error of voluntarism).82 Bhaskar’s conception of society therefore accommodates both the idea of the reality of the social and the importance of human agency. His conception of society is similar to Sandel’s vision of the subject. We always find society ready made, just as the subject always finds itself ready made. It is something we can reproduce or transform, but not something we can create anew. This places limits on our capacity to reconstruct it according to our preferences, just as there are limits on our ability to reconstruct ourselves according to our preferences. It also places limits on our ability to gain knowledge of it, just as there are limits on our ability to get to know ourselves. Neither society nor ourselves as subjects is ever completely transparent to ourselves. Realist philosophers are concerned to reclaim the world as a reality external to our cogni- tions of it, in the face of both empiricism and idealism (and latterly postmodernism). All of these schools ended up viewing the external world as either unknowable, or illusory. It employs a stratified ontology, allocating causal powers and emergent properties to the different levels of the world. This provides a very appealing way to conceive of both the subject and society as mutually-constitutive realities. According to Margaret Archer both the subject and society are the result of emergent properties.83 Both can be viewed as complex systems, as I mentioned above, with a reality of their own. Against postmodernism and social constructionism (and Durkheim) she argues that the subject consists of ‘personal emergent properties’ that are need- ed to make sense of sociability. Role performance by subjects would be impossible in the absence of a subject with a sense of its own continuity and thus self-identity. This subject, in concert with other subjects, has the capacity to transform society, yet it is also partly the result of social conditioning. This, realist notion of society and the subject is in my view superior to both that of Durkheim (and social constructionism) and the atomistic subject of liberal theory. However, Durkheim’s vision of the subject is problematic for another reason, related to the dif- ference between Sandel’s first (instrumental) and second (sentimental) conceptions of community. It is never clear if the subject is inherently selfish, and thus needful of restraint by the common morality, or inherently both egoistic and altruistic. Most of the time, he opts for the first position, but sometimes he seems to mean the second. Part of the confusion is generated by the different 81 Sandel Liberalism (note 54 above) at xi; R Bhaskar ‘On the Possibility of Social Scientific Knowledge and the Limits of Naturalism’ in J Mepham & DH Rubin (eds) Issues in Marxist philosophy Vol 3: Epis- temology, Science, Ideology (1979) at 125. 82 Bhaskar ‘On the Possibility’ (note 81 above) at 120. 83 M Archer ‘The Private Life of The Social Agent: What Difference Does It Make?’ in J Cruickshank (ed) Critical Realism. The Difference it Makes (2003) 91. parts he identified in the personality.84 Lying below the individual and social parts of the person- ality is what Durkheim called ‘physical man’.85 This is the consciousness that we have of our own bodies and feelings. It is the field of psychological (rather than social) facts, dealing with percep- tions such as hunger, sadness, anger, love and so on. Superimposed on this is ‘social man’, which is the higher parts of the human personality, consisting of individual and social aspects. ‘Physical man’, concerned as it is with its own perceptions, is selfish, and thus needs to be restrained. On the other hand, Durkheim also suggested that people have an inherent need for social harmony and interaction with others, and that they come to value this harmony very much once they have experienced it.86 This seems to ascribe altruistic inclinations to ‘physical man’, which leads to a confusing picture. The basic problem, as Lukes points out, is that Durkheim tried to avoid using psychological notions in his concern to make the case for soci- ology as a discipline.87 However, in the process he inevitably smuggled in many psychological ideas, but did not theorise them properly, thus causing confusion. Unlike the vagueness surrounding Durkheim’s views of the inclinations of ‘physical man’, he was very clear in his views on the collective consciousness. The collective consciousness, he said, is altruistic. The collective consciousness represents the voice of society within us; it is, conse- quently, our collective conscience at the same time as it is our collective consciousness. As far as the individual part of our consciousness is concerned, Durkheim suggested that it is altruis- tic in an egoistic way.88 He seems to have understood this as meaning that each of us is socia- ble (altruistic) in an individualistic (egoistic) way. But this causes even more confusion, because it implies that individualism is necessarily selfish, something he has just denied. XII Conclusion Durkheim presented a very meticulous critique of free-market capitalism, and a sophisticated and thoughtful defence of communitarianism. In his concern to establish the reality of the social and the essential role it has to play in a cohesive and just society, he did lean too much to the social side, and he did not give enough attention to the subject’s capacity for self-reflection and agency. This mistake is repeated in the social constructionist accounts of the subject that is so prominent today. Durkheim spent much time considering the forms of communality that would be appropriate to a modern society. His alternative of the occupational groups have their short- comings in a context where many people are unemployed on a long-term basis. Because they will form part of the public sphere and do not address the private sphere of the family, they also have shortcomings from a gender perspective, something that Durkheim, like his contempo- raries, did not seriously consider. Durkheim also underestimated the staying power of tradi- tional forms of community, such as religion and ethnicity. Nevertheless, it is fair to say that his alternative of the occupational group was never really tried, and deserves greater scrutiny. The same can be said for his possible contribution to the liberal-communitarian debate. The Just Community 127 84 Gelderblom (note 20 above). 85 Durkheim Suicide (note 32 above) at 213. 86 Durkheim The Division of Labour (note 4 above) at xliii. 87 Lukes Émile Durkheim (note 30 above). 88 Durkheim The Division of Labour (note 4 above) at 146. Theology and the Fulfillment of Social and Economic Rights: Some Theoretical Considerations N I C O N K O O P M A N Beyers Naudé Centre For Public Theology, Stellenbosch University I Introduction It is an important presupposition of this article and in fact of the research project of which this book is a product that theory-formation is indispensable for addressing social and economic challenges. In fact the Greek root of the word ‘theory’ suggests that theory literally has to do with the way we see and think about the world. These ways of thinking and seeing influence our practices.1 The claim is legitimately made that there is no practice without theory.2 It is then indeed a challenge of the research project to impact on the theories, the ways of seeing and thinking regarding social and economic justice. Impacting the way appropriate role players see and think about social and eco- nomic rights paves the way for an impact on the various practices regarding social and economic justice. Prevailing practices might be revisited and transformed. Where constructive practices are not existing the way may be paved for the development of such practices. In this article it is argued that theology may contribute to this process of theory-formation. Theology, as critical reflection upon the faith and practices of religion,3 through the ages indeed impacted on the theories that informed and guided the practices of faith and other communi- ties regarding political, social and economic justice. Unfortunately this role has not always been constructive. Historically religion and theology fulfilled an ambiguous role.4 It made negative as well as constructive contributions to the wellbeing of society, also with regard to social and economic justice. The history of the world is full of examples of the negative effects of religion, 1 The Greek word (theõreõ) literally means to look or gaze at, to see, to perceive, to think, to discern and even to participate in and experience what you see. See in this regard G Abbott-Smith A Manual Greek Lexicon of the New Testament (1977) at 206-207. 2 For an extensive outline of the idea that all practices are theory-laden practices, see D Browning A Fundamental Practical Theology. Descriptive and Strategic Proposals (1996). 3 This paper focuses mainly on Christian churches and theology. However, various points of convergence with other religions do exist. 4 For a good analysis of the potential destructive role of religions, see S Huntington The Clash of Civilizations and the Remaking of Worldorder (1997). For very helpful outlines of the ambiguous roles of religion with regard to social and economic justice, see two collections of essays in P Berger (ed) The Desecularization of the World. Resurgent Religion and World Politics (1999) and also W Green and J Neusner (eds) The Religion Factor. An Introduction to how Religion Matters (1996). The work of Roman Catholic theologian Hans Küng regarding the potential destructive and constructive roles of religion is also of importance. See amongst others H Küng (ed) Yes to a Global Ethic (1996) and also H Küng and KJ Kuschel (eds) A Global Ethic. The Declaration of the Parliament of World Religions (1993). eg crusades, inquisitions, killing of those who differ on doctrinal issues, killing of millions in the name of holy wars, and the legitimation of evils like Nazism and apartheid. There is, however, also ample evidence of the constructive contributions of religion. The protest of the Confessing Church in Germany during the Nazi regime and the public involvement and wit- ness of so-called struggle churches during the quest for inclusive democracy and during the first decade of democracy in South Africa bear witness to the redemptive role of religion and theology.5 This ambiguous role of churches also prevailed specifically with regard to the development of human rights. Churches did not only in its long history contribute to the violation of human rights, as practices like the subjugation of women and the justification of evils like racism and slavery demonstrate, but churches also offered theological arguments,6 albeit meagre ones, against the notion of human rights. On the other hand, there are ample evidence that the Christian tradition offered theological arguments in favour of, advocated for and helped to lay the foundation for the establishment of human rights.7 Villa-Vicencio makes a strong case to prove that the theological endeavours of mainly south- ern churches, in cooperation with churches in northern countries as well as partners in civil soci- ety and government, helped to ensure that so-called second and third generation rights be taken up into bills of rights more explicitly. In this regard Villa-Vicencio refers with appreciation to the positions of the Lutheran World Federation, the World Alliance of Reformed Churches and the Roman Catholic Church.8 The emphasis in these ecumenical positions on second and third gen- eration rights was encouraged to a high extent by Christians in southern countries. During the struggle years South African theologians developed, in dialogue and cooperation with struggle organizations in the political sphere and in civil society and also with other reli- gious and secular traditions, a vision of social and economic justice. They articulated this vision publicly and eloquently during the years of the anti-apartheid struggle. This communication of the vision was done in the media and in theological studies, declarations and even an official confession of faith.9 It would perhaps not be pretentious to say that theology did not only impact on the public opinion during those years, but that it also helped to prepare the way for the eventual articulation of this vision of social and economic justice in the South African Bill of Rights. Theology and the Fulfilment of Social and Economical Rights 129 5 For an outline of the constructive role of theology during and after apartheid see amongst others P Walshe ‘Christianity and the Anti-apartheid Struggle: The Prophetic Voice within Divided Churches’ in R Elphick and R Davenport (eds) Christianity in South Africa. A Political, Social and Cultural History (1997) at 383 – 399, and J de Gruchy ‘African Theology: South Africa’ in D Ford (ed) The Modern Theologians. An Introduction to Christian Theology in the Twentieth Century (1997) at 445 – 454 and N Koopman ‘Some Comments About Public Theology Today’ (2003) Journal of Theology for Southern Africa 1 – 19. 6 Typical arguments are: humans are sinners who can only talk about grace and privileges and not claims and rights; salvation is spiritual and private, and not political and economical. Therefore religious matters on the one hand, and political and economic matters on the other hand should be separated. 7 For an outline of the constructive role of theology in the development of the notion of human rights, see C Villa-Vicencio A Theology of Reconstruction: Nationbuilding and Human Rights (1992) and J de Gruchy Christianity and Democracy. A Theology for a Just World Order (1995), and Walshe (note 5 above) at 383 – 399. 8 See Villa-Vicencio (note 7 above) at 131 – 153. 9 The famous 1985 Kairos Document is one of the best examples of a theological declaration that opposed injus- tices. The document opposes so-called state and church theologies and opted for prophetic theology that spells out visions of an alternative society that cherishes justice. See The Kairos Document: Challenge to the Church: A Theological Comment on the Political Crisis in South Africa (1985). The former Dutch Reformed Mission Church even adopted a confession in which social and economic justice is described as not only a social and economic matter, but a moral matter, moreover, a matter of faith. See The Confession of Belhar (1986). 1 3 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E Theology indeed made a crucial contribution to acknowledging social and economic justice issues as human rights issues. It contributed to the development of so-called second and third generation rights. The challenge for theology now is to explore ways of contributing to the ful- fillment, implementation and actual practicing of these rights; to develop theories, ways of see- ing and thinking, ways of public thinking, that foster the practical and concrete enforcement, implementation and fulfillment of these rights. Keeping the vision of social and economic jus- tice alive is important, ensuring the articulation of this vision in bills of rights is important. But exploring ways of ensuring that this vision be embodied now calls for our attention. This paper consequently considers the role of theology in developing theories that might enhance the fulfillment10 of social and economic rights11 and the eventual dawning of a more just society. The potential contribution of theology to the process of theory building that serves the fulfillment of social and economic rights is investigated with reference to the dialogue and cooperation of theology with three environments, namely broader society, the academy and reli- gious organizations, specifically churches.12 This threefold distinction is very helpful, though room should be left for the fact that the three realms are not neatly separated from each other. They do impact on each other, and some themes are addressed in all three though with differ- ent emphases and modes. The emphasis of dialogue and cooperation does not only build on the style in which theolo- gy was done by so-called struggle theologians in the apartheid era. It spells out the mode in which theology is to be done that seeks serious attention in a pluralistic society. The outline of these various dialogues and cooperations will hopefully verify this point. 10 Human rights scholar, A Gewirth ‘Are there any Absolute Rights?’ in J Waldron Theories of Rights (1984) at 92, offers a useful distinction on the different applications of human rights: ‘A right is fulfilled when the correlative duty is carried out, ie when the required action is performed or the prohibited action is not per- formed. A right is infringed when the correlative duty is not carried out, ie when the required action is not performed or the prohibited action is performed. Thus someone’s right to life is infringed when the pro- hibited action of killing him is performed, someone’s right to medical care is infringed when the required action of providing him with medical care is not performed. A right is violated when it is unjustifiably infringed, when the required action is unjustifiably not performed or the prohibited action is unjustifiably performed. And a right is overridden when it is justifiably infringed, so that there is sufficient justification for not carrying out the correlative duty, and the required action is justifiably not performed or the pro- hibited action is justifiably performed.’ 11 Economic and social rights are distinguished from so-called political and civil rights. In the first centuries of the development of human rights the emphasis was on the latter rights. During the second part of the twentieth century economic and social rights were increasingly emphasized, especially at initiative of so- called poorer southern countries. For the distinction between three generations of rights, namely first gen- eration (blue) rights, second generation (red) rights and third generation (green) rights, see J van der West- huizen ‘The Human Rights Debate in South Africa’ in K Nürnberger (ed) A Democratic Vision for South Africa. Political Realism and Christian Response (1991) at 471 - 487. The idea of generations of rights should not give the impression that the social, economic and environmental rights did not feature in the ear- lier phases of the development of human rights. However, they did not receive the same level of attention as the so-called first generation rights. 12 This threefold distinction is borrowed from North American Catholic theologian David Tracy who identi- fies the church, the academy and the broader society as the three publics, reference groups or social loca- tions that theology engages with. See his The Analogical Imagination. Christian Theology and the Culture of Pluralism (1981) at 3, 5. Tracy (at 21) is of opinion that all theology is in some meaningful sense church theology, ie ecclesial theology. Theology develops in a sense from within the church as both a pneumato- logical and sociological body. When he refers to the church as one of the publics of theology, he especially has this sociological nature of the church in mind. II Theology in Dialogue and Cooperation with Broader Society In investigating the role of theology in developing thinking that will enhance the fulfillment of social and economic rights, dialogue and cooperation with broader society is required. Dirkie Smit13 offers a very helpful description of modern democratic societies. He is of opinion that modern societies consist of four spheres, namely the political and economic spheres, as well as the spheres of civil society and public opinion formation.14 The political sphere focuses on the state, government, political power and the control and regulating of public life. The economic sphere entails aspects like the so-called autonomous market-economy, globalisation, ecology, science and technology. Civil society focuses on themes relating to the relationship between theology and, amongst others, the institutions, organiza- tions, associations and movements of civil society which, independently from the state and economy, strive to enhance the quality of life, satisfy the needs and foster the interests of peo- ple, change the nature of society and build the common good, that is a life of quality for all. Schools, legal bodies, cultural and sports clubs and the neighbourhood are all institutions of civil society. Sociologically speaking churches are part of civil society, albeit institutions with both a sociological and pneumatological character. The area of public opinion formation focus- es on themes like the nature of society, the common foundational values for society, common challenges and common priorities for society. The ensuing public opinion paves the way for jointly striving towards the common good.15 The dialogue and cooperation of theology with these spheres take place in appropriate modes. In this regard the typology of North American theologian James Gustafson16 is very helpful. He identifies four varieties of moral discourse which suggest four ways in which theol- ogy can engage with these spheres. The prophetic discourse takes on the form of indictment and a more utopian form. Indict- Theology and the Fulfilment of Social and Economical Rights 131 13 See D Smit ‘Oor die Unieke Openbare Rol van die Kerk’ (1996) Tydskrif vir Geesteswetenskappe 190–198. 14 Tracy (note 12 above) at 6 -14 divides the public of society into three spheres, namely the realm of the tech- noeconomic structure that deals with the organization and allocation of goods and services; the realm of the polity where the aim is to embody social justice in the traditions and institutions of society through the legitimate use of power and force, and the regulation of conflict within the rule of law. The realm of cul- ture which includes art and religion explores and expresses the meaning and values of individual, group and communal existence. 15 Smit’s distinctions coincide with the distinctions of Jürgen Habermas. For him the democratic public con- sists of four spheres. At its centre are government, the civil service, judiciary, parliament, political parties, elections and party competition. Outside this core system, but still belonging to the state is an inner periph- ery of institutions such as regulatory agencies with powers delegated by the state. The second public sphere, which is part of the outer periphery, is organizations that Habermas calls customers, ie business associa- tions, labour unions and private organizations. The third public sphere, which is also part of the outer periphery consists of organizations that he calls the suppliers, ie voluntary associations, churches, new social movements and public interest groups. Fourthly he makes room for the public opinion that is formed by the dialogue of public interest groups and professionals who, as the sensors of society, identify, draw attention to and interpret social problems and who, with the aid of the media, propose solutions and apply pressure that can bring forth change that will better the situation of especially the disadvantaged. See J Habermas Between Facts and Norms (1996). 16 See J Gustafson ‘An Analysis of Church and Society Social Ethical Writings’ (1988) 40 Ecumenical Review at 267 -278; ‘Varieties of Moral Discourse: Prophetic, Narrative, Ethical and Policy’ (1988) The Stob Lectures of Calvin College and Seminary; ‘Moral Discourse About Medicine: A Variety of Forms’ (1990) Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 125 -142. 1 3 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E ment points to the roots of moral or social problems. Utopian discourse evokes a hopeful vision. It proclaims an ideal state of affairs in the future and allures and motivates people towards its realization. In the narrative discourse stories and parables are told of significant events and of moral heroes in the community and tradition. These stories sustain common memory in a community. They shape the consciences, moral identities and characters of members of the community. More than a rigorous casuistic argument stories provide illumi- nation and help in the process of moral decisionmaking. The ethical or technical discourse uses philosophical and rigorous modes of moral argumentation. Logic, precise distinctions, precision in use of concepts like justice and rights and the identification of the rational grounds of autonomous ethics, which might be backed by Christian convictions which can be shared with non-believers, are typical features of this discourse. The policy discourse is the discourse of the policy and decision makers in society. They deal with questions like: what is desirable within the constraints of what is possible; do we have power to affect change, what are the time frames for the achievement of ends; do we have all the necessary information and knowledge? The policy discourse entails that we have to distinguish between matters of ethical principle and the inferences we draw for policy. We can be more certain about the first than the second. In the dialogue and cooperation of theology with the various spheres of society on the achievement of social and economic justice attention is to be given to all these discourses. The vision of an alternative society that energises and opens innovative possibilities should be spelled out.17 Clear critique should be voiced where injustices exist. The grass roots stories of poverty and suffering are to be heard, but also the stories of even smaller achievements and suc- cesses. The technical discourse is of immense importance. It suggests that it is not enough to spell out broad principles and visions of justice. The hard work of critical, scientific, interdisci- plinary and intersectoral analysis and deliberation which can lead to even preliminary solutions that are jointly reached is of crucial importance. Engagement with these various discourses paves the way for appropriate interventions in the policymaking processes on different levels of governance and authority in different spheres of society.18 In engaging these spheres it is important that theology resist the temptation to fulfill the role of being the only watchdog of society that just engages in the prophetic discourse of critique 17 Envisioning opens up creative, innovative and surprising possibilities that technical reflection alone cannot. Old Testament theologian Walter Brueggemann The Prophetic Imagination (1978) at 13 argues that envi- sioning, imagining, enables us to see new possibilities that are in contrast to the dominant gloomy before- hand possibilities. Vision creates hope in situation of despair and energy where people feel powerless. Vision, on the other hand, helps us to be clearly aware of the shortcomings of our endeavours and policies. Vision opens the door for courageous and constructive criticism. Various forms of the church help to devel- op this vision of an alternative society. North American theologian Stanley Hauerwas argues that ethicists function like artists. What they see determine not only their choices and actions but also who they are. We are and we do what we see. Vision determines ethics. See S Hauerwas Vision and Virtue: Essays in Christian Ethical Reflection (1974); Truthfulness and Tragedy: Further Investigations in Christian Ethics (1977); A Community of Character: Toward a Constructive Christian Social Ethic (1981); The Peaceable Kingdom: A Primer in Christian Ethics (1983) and various other works. 18 Theology’s dialogue and interaction with broader spheres of society occur mainly through the denomina- tional and ecumenical church. There are instances where theologians make direct input in their personal and professional capacities, eg in ethical committees of hospitals, ethical committees in the business and public media sectors as well as parliamentary portfolio committees. The bulk of inputs are however made through church bodies. The remarks made here are therefore also relevant to the section on the institutional church below. and indictment. In the same vein it is not responsible theology to merely spell out the vision of a good society.19 The road of partnership that institutions like the South African Council of Churches currently opt for is perhaps the most fruitful path to follow. In this cooperation it is important that theology not be co-opted by the agenda of the state.20 A guiding principle for this cooperation is to continually ask what the impact of dialogue, cooperation, compromises and policies are on poor and vulnerable people. One of the most cherished notions in Christian theology that Liberation Theology reminded us about during the 1960s to 1980s is the convic- tion that God is in special way the God of the poor, the destitute and the wronged. The acid test for our social and economic discourses, policies and priorities is the question on how they impact on the most vulnerable in society. Where the engagement of theology with political institutions, business and trade unions, sport and cultural bodies, schools and other organs of civil society, different forms of the mod- ern communication media, takes place within the parameters, modes and style outlined above, these encounters might prove to be fruitful for the quest of developing new ways of thinking about and new practices for the fulfillment of social and economic rights. III Theology in Dialogue and Cooperation with the Academy Tracy21 describes the academy as that public or social location of theology where serious, crit- ical scientific enquiry takes place with other academic disciplines. In its engagement with the academy theology is challenged to provide arguments that all reasonable people from diverse religious and secular traditions can recognize as reasonable. In this discourse appeals are made to universal faculties such as experience, intelligence, rationality and responsibility. Claims are stated with appropriate warrants, backings and rebuttal procedures. He also pleads that although theologians confess allegiance to a specific religious tradition or to a praxis movement bearing religious significance, they should abstract themselves from these faith commitments for the sake of critical analysis of religious and theological claims by outsiders and by those who belong to the tradition. There are of course many theologians who would oppose Tracy on this point. They would argue that you need not abstract and distance yourself from your faith com- mitments in order to do critical and honest introspection into the cognitive claims of your tra- dition. Such a withdrawal for the sake of honest scientific enquiry is viewed as being dishonest. With an appeal to Thomas Kuhn’s paradigm theory Dutch systematic theologian Gijsbert van den Brink,22 supports the later developments in the philosophy of science discourse which make room for adherence to particularistic commitments in the scientific endeavour. Although Theology and the Fulfilment of Social and Economical Rights 133 19 For an analysis of the prophetic task of churches in the context of poverty in a democratic society see N Koopman ‘Freedom of Religion and the Prophetic Role of the Church’ (2002) 43 NGTT 237 – 247 and also my ‘Let the Plight of the Poor be Heard. Prophetic Speaking about Poverty Today’ (2004) 45 NGTT 440 – 451. 20 For a description of the danger of Constantinianism see N Koopman ‘Tussen die Duiwel van Konstantinisme en die Diep Blou See van Sektarisme – Kerk en Staat Verhoudinge in Post-apartheid Suid- Afrika’ (2001) 43 NGTT 135 – 146. The concept ‘Constantinianism’ derives from the era since Caesar Constantine when the once persecuted Christian religion became state religion after the conversion of Constantine to Christianity in the fourth century. The concept refers to any co-option of the church by the agenda of the state. 21 See Tracy (note 12 above) at 56 – 59. 22 See G van den Brink Een Publieke Zaak. Theologie tussen Geloof en Wetenskap (2004). 1 3 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E he reckons that there is something to be learned from older important philosophies of science,23 it remains his conviction that these approaches do not take the significant and determinative particularistic influences like faith commitments of scientists seriously enough. In the encounter with the academic public theology makes the choice for scientific reflection, for making faith convictions as far as possible rationally accessible to all reasonable people, for constructing arguments that pass the test of coherence, consistency and logical reasoning. However, theology does not have to distance itself from its faith commitments, but takes care that such commitments do not exclude scientific scrutiny. The age-old Christian notion of fides quaerens intellectum (faith seeking understanding) that Anselm of Canterbury framed in the 11/12th century needs fresh application in this dialogue of theology with the academic public. Against this background sketched in the previous paragraphs some suggestions can be made about the contribution of theology in the dialogue and cooperation with the academy. A first contribution of theology might be to help dialogue partners to view the challenge of the implementation of human rights not only as a political, social, economic, legal, philosoph- ical and sociological challenge but as a moral challenge. Morality has to do with the wellbeing, happiness and wholeness of human beings and other creatures. Something is morally good when it serves this wellbeing and it is morally bad if it does not.24 If theology embarks on this endeavour it strengthens those in other disciplines who already view the challenge of social and economic justice as a moral challenge. Some theologians are of the opinion that the contribution of theology to social-ethical and economic-ethical challenges is merely to help portraying these as ethical challenges and to pro- vide a meaning-giving framework that is based in religious or secular belief systems, and that serves to motivate people to participate in the quest to address these challenges. Other theolo- gians, however, are of opinion that theology indeed can make a unique contribution to the con- tents of the debate.25 I am of the opinion that theology might enrich the contents of the discourse on the imple- mentation of human rights. Theology might be able, for instance, to assist the discourse in reaching thicker descriptions of justice. Elsewhere26 I described various forms of justice and 23 Van den Brink reasons that despite their weaknesses older philosophies of science still pose some important challenges. Logical positivism challenges us to ensure that cognitive meaningful statements be verifiable as far as possible; confirmationism teaches us that it is much more difficult to confirm so-called non-existence statements then existence statements; the falsification theory of Karl Popper challenges us to open ourselves to criticism, to continuous disturbance and critical opposition by researchers who do not just take our posi- tions for granted. See Van den Brink (note 22 above) at 219–221. 24 For a definition of morality in terms of this notion of security and wellbeing, see B Birch and L Rasmussen Bible and Ethics in the Christian Life (1989) at 38-39. 25 For an extensive discussion of these two opposing views regarding the contribution of religion and theolo- gy to ethical challenges see N Koopman ‘The Role of Tradition in Moral Decisionmaking and Moral Consensus’ (2004) 45 NGTT 838 – 848. In this article I discuss the so-called liberal position of Dutch schol- ar Harry Kuitert who reckons that religion and theology do not contribute to the contents of morality, but that it merely serves as protector, feeder and sustainer of morality, and as motivator for morally good liv- ing. I bring this position in dialogue with the so-called postliberal position of Stanley Hauerwas who reck- ons that religion and theology fulfill a crucial role with regard to the contents of morality since morality is in essence agent, narrative and community-dependent. 26 For a brief outline of utilitarian, libertarian, communitarian and egalitarian theories of justice and the theo- ry proposed by theologian Karin Lebacqz, see N Koopman ‘Justice and Land Reform’ (2004) paper read at the international conference on land reform in Utrecht, Netherlands, and accepted for publication in Studies in Reformed Theology. Karin Lebacqz expresses appreciation for Rawls’ emphasis of the least advantaged, Nozick’s valuing of freedom, the emphasis of the priority of the poor in the 1986 pastoral letter on eco- then opted for an understanding of justice as compassionate justice. Hereby I mean that justice has two dimensions that can be derived from two different words for justice in Hebrew. Tsedaqah refers to the sacrifice that is required to transform people into just people and into people who are also willing to make sacrifices for the sake of the other. Mispat refers to foren- sic justice that is enforced by legal measures. These measures would include contemporary notions like human rights. Compassionate justice therefore would argue that legal justice and the ethos of compassion and sacrifice cooperate to bring forth a life of justice and dignity for all humans and the environment. Making the notion of sacrifice part of the discourse about social and economic justice might enhance our progress towards fruitful solutions. The impli- cation of the notion of sacrifice for current and potentially new political, economic and legal measures of reparation for the sake of higher levels of equilibrium, might be an important part of the discourse on social and economic justice. IV Theology in Dialogue and Cooperation with Churches The dialogue and cooperation of theology with churches is very important. The mutual impact of theology and this realm is also prevalent as with the two other publics. For various reasons churches do have the potential to make a significant contribution to the realizing of social and economic rights. The potential of churches is amongst others reflected in the high percentage of people belonging to religions in South African society. The dawning of modernisation in its institutionalized forms of democratic state, market-driven economy, civil society and sophisti- cated and influential public media, as well as its Zeitgeist of individualism and rationalism have not lead to secularization in South Africa. On the contrary, most recent statistics indicate that more than 90% of South Africans belong to one or the other form of religion. The percentage of Christians rose during the last few years to almost 80%.27 It should, however, be noted that although modernization has not been accompanied by sec- ularization, it has affected religion in terms of modernity’s central feature of the fragmentation of society into various autonomous life spheres. This development has created a high poten- tial for the privatization of religion. So although people might still be religious, religion is removed from the various public spheres of society. The potential of such a privatized religion to impact positively on society is very low. On the contrary, private religion does not only imply withdrawal from society, it often also entails destructive forms of religion and morali- ty, eg fundamentalism, intolerance, moral absolutism and judgementalism. When we embark on the investigation of the role of churches in the advancement of social and economic rights these facts should be taken into consideration. Whilst doing this we should also always be Theology and the Fulfilment of Social and Economical Rights 135 nomic justice of the North American Catholic Bishops, and the recognition of the epistemological privilege of the poor, ie God is only known in the doing of justice by liberation theologian Jose Miranda. Based on these positions she constructs her own position that calls for more attention to the narratives of the mar- ginalized in the discourse about social and economic justice. 27 See in this regard H Hendriks The Future of the Church, the Church of the Future (2004) Unpublished Inaugural lecture, University of Stellenbosch. This trend of growth in religiosity is not limited to South Africa. Peter Berger has replaced his secularization thesis with a de-secularisation thesis. After arguing since the sixties of the previous century that secularization will spread all over the world and that religion will be increasingly marginalized he now observes growth of religiosity in all parts of the world, especially in South America, Africa and Asia. Although Western Europe is highly secularized he is of opinion that religion survives in non-institu- tional form in some of the Western European regions. See Berger (note 4 above) at 1-18. 1 3 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E aware of the ambiguous history of religion in social matters as described earlier in this article. The challenge to theology is to assist and guide churches in discovering and actualizing their constructive potential with regard to the challenge of the realization of social and economic rights. In investigating the role of churches in the fulfillment of social and economic rights, Dirkie Smit’s identification of six forms of the church might be helpful.28 The first four forms consti- tute the church as institution. They are worship services, local congregations with their various practices, denominations and ecumenical bodies. The other two forms constitute the church as organism, namely individual Christians in their normal daily roles in family, work, neighbour- hood etcetera, and individual Christians in voluntary organizations. (a) Worship services have the potential to transform people into just people who can enhance the social and economic transformation of society. The impact of worship on ethics, also economic ethics is increasingly treasured by a growing number of authors. In a recent pub- lication American theologians Stanley Hauerwas and Samuel Wells pleaded for an end to the separation of worship and ethics that developed under the influence of Immanuel Kant. From different perspectives various authors demonstrate how worship impacts on our eth- ical choices, policies and moral living in various walks of life, specifically in the area of social and economic justice.29 The transformative, subversive and revolutionary potential of worship services are investigated by an increasing number of theologians. Those partic- ipating in worship see alternative realities that are in conflict to the prior realities of a world where injustice reigns supreme and they are transformed to participate in the building of these alternative realities. Those who pray for daily bread, see a world where there is bread for everyone and they participate in creating such a world. (b) Various practices of congregations also enhance the fulfillment of social and economic rights. The definition of practices according to American theologians Craig Dykstra and Dorothy Bass30 is very helpful. They define practices as follows: ‘By “Christian practices” we mean things Christian people do together over time to address fundamental human needs in response to and in the light of God’s active presence for the life of the world.’31 Practices refer to cooperative and meaningful human endeavours in which certain beliefs, virtues and skills are entwined with certain behaviours, relationships and symbols.32 For the purpose of this article I briefly refer only to two important Christian practices that impact constructively on the quest for economic justice. Stanley Hauerwas writes clearly about the role of baptism and eucharist as Christian practices that impact on public life, specifically on the quest for social and economic justice. He states that baptism and eucharist are not only motives or causes for our social work, they are our effective social work. In them we see most clearly the marks of God’s kingdom in the world.33 Elsewhere he describes how the celebration of the eucharist in the United Methodist congregation of 28 See D Smit ‘Oor die Kerk as Unieke Samelewingsverband’ (1996) Tydskrif vir Geesteswetenskappe at 119 – 129. 29 See S Hauerwas and S Wells (eds) The Blackwell Companion to Christian Ethics (2004). 30 See C Dykstra and D Bass ‘A Theological Understanding of Christian Practices’ in M Volf and D Bass Practicing Theology. Beliefs and Practices in Christian Life (2002) at 13-32. 31 See Dykstra and Bass (note 30 above) at 18. 32 See Dykstra and Bass (note 30 above) at 19-21. 33 See S Hauerwas The Peaceable Kingdom. A Primer in Christian Ethics (1983) at 108. South Band, Indiana, has lead to meal sharing with poor members of the neighbourhood that made it clear ‘that we were not simply another social agency that does a little good, but a people called out to witness to God’s presence in the world. That presence which comes in the meal we share sustained that church’s ability to be present in that neighbour- hood as a symbol that all was not lost’.34 (c) Denominations and ecumenical bodies can embark on the so-called priestly task of show- ing solidarity with the marginalized and the wronged. This care, compassion and solidari- ty are expressed in the various diaconal services of churches, amongst others homes for the aged, disabled, orphans (especially the growing number of aids related orphans), day care centres, crèches, after school care centres for children whose parents are working long hours, church schools, soup kitchens and other feeding schemes, shelters for refugees and victims of disasters like burnt down informal settlements, employment creation initiatives and entrepreneurial courses and initiatives. Many of these initiatives are undertaken in cooperation with role players in other spheres of society, amongst others governmental institutions, businesses, trade unions and even the media. These priestly practices of soli- darity and care are not small endeavours to fulfill social and economic rights in humble and preliminary ways. This direct involvement in the plight of those who do not experience humane living conditions also constructively inform, influence and inspire thinking on the fulfillment of social and economic rights and justice. Denominations and ecumenical bodies also fulfill the prophetic task of clearly spelling out the vision of a good society where people enjoy a life of dignity and justice. This prophetic task also involves a critique of society where the conditions of this good society are not met. Through declarations of faith and even confessions of faith churches spell out this vision and offer this constructive critique. A very recent example of the involvement of ecumeni- cal church bodies on this level is the adoption of a processus confessionis, that means engaging in a process of confessing faith, on economic justice by the World Alliance of Reformed Churches, the Lutheran World Federation and the World Council of Churches. This processus confessionis is the initiative of the Southern African Alliance of Reformed Churches (SAARC) in which Stellenbosch theologian Russel Botman, who was then presi- dent of SAARC, played a pivotal role.35 The thinking on matters of social and economic justice in many Reformed Christians in Southern Africa, as well as in other parts of the world are increasingly influenced by the Confession of Belhar. In October 2004 Christians from Reformed churches in South Africa, other African countries, Belgium, Germany, The Netherlands, Sweden and the USA met in Stellenbosch at the Beyers Naudé Centre for Public Theology for an international conference on the theme Confessing and Embodying Belhar and Barmen Today. The theme of this conference suggests that Christians view social and economic justice as a faith issue. This means to confess faith in God is to work for social and economic justice.36 Churches on denominational and ecumenical level also have the responsibility to intervene Theology and the Fulfilment of Social and Economical Rights 137 34 See S Hauerwas Christian Existence Today. Essays on Church, World and Living in Between (1995) at 124. 35 For a discussion of this processus confessionis, see N Koopman ‘ ‘‘… in a special way the God of the poor, the destitute and the wronged…”. A Basic and Neglected Conviction of (Reformed) Theology?’ in P Coertzen (ed) 350 Years Reformed 1652-2002 (2002) 252 -260. 36 The Confession of Belhar (note 9 above). The Barmen Declaration is a confessional document that was adopted in 1934 by the Confessing Church in the city of Barmen, Germany. The Christians in this Con- fessing Church opposed the growth of Nazism in Germany. 1 3 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E in public policy processes.37 It is crucial to help ensure that laws are formulated that enhance the vision and ideals of justice and dignity spelled out in the Bill of Rights. For this purpose various denominations and ecumenical bodies have already established public pol- icy liaison offices at national parliament in Cape Town, amongst others the South African Council of Churches, the South African Catholic Bishops Conference, the Dutch Reformed Church as well as the Baptist Church. These bodies do not only influence the public policy processes through presentations to the portfolio committees of parliament. They also con- scientise and inform local congregations and individual Christians on public policy matters, amongst others specific issues of social and economic justice. One of the remarkable achievements of these offices is the annual Peoples Budget initiative with trade unions and other institutions of civil society. These partners undertake a critical evaluation of the national budget in terms of its impact on poor people. They also suggest constructive alter- natives. Denominational and ecumenical bodies are also challenged to even inform local worship services regarding issues of social and economic justice through appropriate infor- mation and guidelines for liturgies.38 (d) Individual Christians in their normal daily roles and in voluntary organizations are equipped by the institutional church to participate in appropriate ways in various sectors of society in the fulfillment of social and economic rights and the achievement of social and economic justice. They are equipped with regard to moral decisionmaking39 on economic matters as well as the embodiment of central economic-ethical values. Without pretending to become economists it is important to have some orientation regarding economic matters in order to be able to impact in an informed and responsible way on the direction these mat- ters are taking at home, school, neighbourhood, local government, business, trade unions, churches and all walks of life. Proper utilization of the media, amongst others newspapers, magazines, radio, television, internet, art and music can enhance this process of influencing the thinking and practices of people regarding social and economic justice matters. Individual Christians in their various affiliations also participate in advocacy and protest 37 North American theologian, JP Wogaman Christian Perspectives on Politics (2000) at 264 – 273 sum- marises the public responsibility of churches as follows: Influencing the public ethos, educating the church’s own membership about particular public issues, participating in advocacy and lobbying initiatives, sup- porting specific political parties and candidates with positive records on civil rights and other social justice issues, encourage lay Christians to establish a Christian political party if circumstances warrant this move, engage in truly extreme situations of oppression in civil disobedience and participation in even violent rev- olutions. The contentious nature of some of these proposals are obvious. 38 In 2004 the Beyers Naudé Centre for Public Theology was requested by the South African Council of Churches to do research on the response of South African churches to the arms deals of the South African government during the first decade of democracy. These findings were tabled at an international conference on the international arms trade in Sweden. One of various suggestions was that ecumenical bodies like the South African Council of Churches provide local congregations with guidelines for liturgies on human secu- rity which entails the building of social and economic justice and peace. During the Anti-apartheid struggle these liturgies played a crucial role in influencing and transforming the thinking of people regarding mat- ters of social and economic justice. See in this regard N Koopman ‘Defence in a Democracy. A Church Perspective on the Postapartheid Defence Review Process’ in K Haglind (ed) Arms Trade. Final Report from the 2nd Ecumenical Conference in Gothenburg (2004). 39 Decision making occurs at the hand of three classical approaches to moral decisionmaking, namely the deontological and teleological as well as virtue approaches to ethics. For very helpful orientations to vari- ous approaches to moral decisionmaking see amongst others M Baron, P Pettit and M Slote Three Methods of Ethics: A Debate (1999); P Singer (ed) A Companion to Ethics (2002); R Lovin Christian Ethics. An Essential Guide (2000). activities for the sake of the materialisation of social and economic justice. These actions which are mainly the initiative of civil society organizations can occur on local, provincial and national levels. Due to the astronomic developments in the area of information tech- nology such actions can take on international dimensions. The protest of civil society in 2003 against the war in Iraq is a very good example of a joint international campaign of civil societies from various parts of the world. Such international actions are crucial in the light of the ambiguous effects of economic globalisation. Individual Christians contribute to ways of thinking and practices that enhance the ful- fillment of social and economic rights by embodying the values that they are campaigning for. The institutional church, through its worship services, congregational practices, denom- inational and ecumenical policies, declarations, confessional statements and public actions and witnesses, contributes to the transformation of individual Christians into people who live with specific virtues. According to North American theologian J Philip Wogaman a virtue is the tendency and predisposition to be and to act in accordance with goodness.40 Virtues are incarnated, embodied, practiced values.41 Where these virtues, with their per- sonal and public dimensions, are cherished and developed,42 significant impact is made on the development of theories and practices that enhance the fulfillment of social and eco- nomic rights. V Conclusion The quest for theories that seek the fulfillment of social and economic rights and the restora- tion of a life of dignity for all is an act of responsibility. The ethics of responsibility gained momentum in the midst of the immense suffering due to amongst others the two destructive world wars of the twentieth century. Political scientists, lawyers, economists, philosophers and theologians joined the search for just, peaceful and sustainable societies where the life of cur- rent and future generations could flourish. North American theologian Helmut Richard Niebuhr43 joined this quest. For him responsibility starts with the question: what is going on Theology and the Fulfilment of Social and Economical Rights 139 40 See J Wogaman Christian Moral Judgment (1988) especially chapter 2. 41 The Christian tradition formulated seven virtues. Four of them are borrowed from Greek philosophical thinking, specifically from Aristotle, and are called the cardinal virtues. Justice entails that people embody fairness, commitment to a life of equality, dignity and and joy for all. Just people are even willing to sacri- fice for the sake of the other. The other three cardinal virtues are temperance, discernment or wisdom, and fortitude or courage. The three theological virtues that complete the list of seven Christian virtues are faith, hope and love. All these virtues impact on a life of social and economic justice and dignity for all. For very helpful accounts of the virtues see besides the works mentioned above about approaches to moral deci- sionmaking also S Hauerwas and C Pinches Christians among the Virtues. Theological Conversations with Ancient and Modern Ethics (1997) and N Richardson ‘Ethics of character and community’ in C Villa- Vicencio and J de Gruchy (eds) Doing Ethics in Context. South African Perspectives (1994) 89 - 101. 42 Recently much work is done in the field of moral and virtue formation. Both the theological and anthro- pological dimensions of these processes are investigated. For a general orientation to the work of moral for- mation see N Koopman and R Vosloo Die Ligtheid van die Lig. Morele Oriëntasie in ‘n Postmoderne Tyd (2002). For a very helpful description of the various modes of moral formation, see the important and famous work of Roman Catholic Dutch theologian J van der Ven Formation of the Moral Self (1998). He identifies seven modes of moral formation, namely discipline, socialization, value transmission, value clar- ification, moral development, emotional development and character formation. 43 See H Niebuhr The Responsible Self. An Essay in Christian Moral Philosophy (1978) especially 12 – 19. 1 4 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E around us? What is happening around us? According to him Christians would add the ques- tion: what is God busy doing in our world? Decades later social scientists in the USA like Robert Bellah and his co-authors would reason in the same vein and argue that democracy can- not succeed if there are not people who pay attention, people who are aware and conscious of what is going on around them.44 Still later the South African anti-apartheid struggle gained momentum when people like Steve Bantu Biko, who is hailed as the father of the Black Consciousness Movement, embarked on an intentional process of conscientisation, of making people aware of not only the oppressive dimensions of their reality, but also of the liberative potential in that reality.45 Three decades later scholars from different disciplines participate in the research project on the enforcement of social and economic rights of which this book is a product. Thereby they embark on this first step of responsible living. They pay attention and see that whilst the so- called first generation rights of the treasured South African Bill of Rights enjoy much attention in public discourse and even in court cases, the so-called second and third generation social and economic rights are limited to the margins of the public discourse. They see that lastmentioned rights are not enforced to the same extent as the former rights. In dialogue with each other they seek ways of addressing this challenge. They strive to build theories that will hopefully assist South African policy makers in different public spheres as well as individual South Africans in all walks of life to see what is going on around them, to pay attention and to address the immense challenges with creativity and innovation. Theology is privileged to participate in this quest. 44 See R Bellah et al Habits of the Heart. Individualism and Commitment in American Life (1985) and also R Bellah et al The Good Society (1991). 45 For his writings on the insights of the Black Consciousness Movement, see S Biko I Write What I Like (2004). The Value of Human Dignity in Interpreting Socio-Economic Rights* S A N D R A L I E B E N B E R G H Oppenheimer Chair for Human Rights, Stellenbosch University …Without the ability to secure the immediate needs of the present, the future is lit- tle more than a far-off possibility, remote both in perception and in reality…** I Introduction The inclusion of socio-economic rights as justiciable rights in the Bill of Rights of South Africa’s Constitution affirms the critical importance of material conditions to human survival and devel- opment.1 In their seminal article, arguing for the constitutional protection of socio-economic rights in South Africa, Craig Scott and Patrick Maklem argued as follows: …Perhaps the strongest reason for including a certain number of economic and social rights is that by constitutionalising half of the human rights equation, South Africans would be constitutionalising only part of what it is to be a full person. A constitution containing only civil and political rights projects an image of truncated humanity. Symbolically, but still brutally it excludes those seg- ments of society for whom autonomy means little without the necessities of life…2 Socio-economic rights are not valued as commodities, but because of what they enable human * Earlier versions of this paper were read at the conference of the SA Journal on Human Rights, ‘Twenty Years of Human Rights Scholarship and Ten-Years of Democracy’ (5 – 7 July 2004), and at the Stellenbosch Institute for Advanced Study (STIAS) seminar on ‘Theories of Social and Economic Justice’ (30 – 31 July 2004). This article first appeared in (2005) 21 SAJHR 1 – 31 and is re-published with kind permission of S Liebenberg, I Currie (editor of SAJHR) and Juta & Co. Participants at both the aforesaid events provid- ed valuable comments and suggestions for which I am indebted. I am also grateful for the comments and insights of my colleagues, André van der Walt and Lourens du Plessis, as well as the suggestions received from the SAJHR editors. Finally, I would like to thank Beth Goldblatt for challenging me to think critical- ly about the limits of human dignity in advancing a transformative constitutional jurisprudence. ** Per Arbour J in Gosselin v Quebec (Attorney General), 2002 SCC 84 at para 392. 1 The preamble of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa Act 108 of 1996 [hereafter ‘the Constitution’] proclaims that it was adopted with the purpose (amongst others) to ‘[i]mprove the quality of life of all citizens and free the potential of each person’. 2 ‘Constitutional Ropes of Sand or Justiciable Guarantees? Social Rights in a New South African Constitution’ (1992) 141 Univ of Pennsylvania LR 1, 29. 1 4 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E beings to do and to be.3 If basic subsistence needs are not met, humans face severe threats to life and health. But, in addition, such deprivation impedes the development of a whole range of human capabilities, including the ability to fulfill life plans and participate effectively in politi- cal, economic and social life.4 It also deprives society of the contributions of all its members.5 Thus both the individual and society are impoverished by our collective failure to ensure living conditions worthy of the dignity of people as both individual and social beings.6 As justiciable rights, socio-economic rights must be interpreted in the context of concrete cases. The courts must determine how much must be provided, to whom, at what pace and in what order of priority. In order to do so, they must explicate the underlying values that guide its interpretation. In so doing, the Court also affirms the values constituting our post-apartheid society.7 3 Martha Nussbaum has provided an influential philosophical justification for constitutional principles aimed at ensuring the conditions for the development and exercise of human capabilities: See particularly M C Nussbaum Women and Human Development – The Capabilities Approach (2000) [hereafter ‘Women and Human Development’]. Her approach focuses ‘on human capabilities, that is, what people are actually able to do and to be – in a way informed by an intuitive idea of a life that is worthy of the dignity of the human being’: Nussbaum (2000) 5. On the relationship between capabilities and human rights, see Nussbaum (2000) 96 – 101; and Nussbaum ‘Capabilities, Human Rights and the Universal Declaration’ in B H Weston & S P Marks (eds) The Future of International Human Rights (1999) 25 - 64. In development economics, the capa- bilities approach to quality of life assessments was pioneered by Amartya Sen through a range of works, including his collaboration of the Human Development Reports of the United Nations Development Programme (UNDP). See, eg, ‘Equality of What’ in A Sen Choice, Welfare and Measurement (1982) 353 – 369, and his recent work Development as Freedom (2001). For Sen, the goal of development should be to expand the capabilities of persons ‘to lead the kind of lives they value – and have reason to value’: Development as Freedom (2001) 18. Nussbaum discusses the differences between her and Sen’s ‘capabilities’ theory at 11 – 15 of Women and Human Development. However, both view the ‘capabilities’ approach as more appropriate to quality of life assessments in human development than many of the traditional alterna- tives. Nussbaum discusses the defects of standard approaches such as GNP per capita, utilitarian approaches (which ask about the total or average utility of the population, as measured by expressions of satisfaction), and approaches focusing on basic resource distribution in Women and Human Development (at 59 – 70). 4 For an account of the impact and experience of poverty in South Africa, see J May Poverty and Inequality in South Africa: Report prepared for the Office of the Executive Deputy President and the Inter-Ministerial Committee for Poverty and Inequality (PIR Report) (1998). See particularly the experiences of poverty doc- umented by The South African Participatory Poverty Assessment: ‘The Experience and Perceptions of Poverty’, Data Research Africa Report (SA-PPA) cited on pp 3 – 5 of the PIR Report. These include: alien- ation from the community, emotional stress and anxiety, food insecurity, the impact of time-consuming domestic tasks particularly for poor women, overcrowded living conditions with the associated loss of pri- vacy, and an increased exposure to violence. The impact of a lack of access to basic services and productive resources such as land on people’s life chances is also vividly illustrated in the Report of the National ‘Speak Out on Poverty’ Hearings convened by the Commission for Gender Equality, the South African Human Rights Commission and the South African NGO Coalition from March – June 1998: D Budlender The People’s Voices (1998). 5 Sen expresses this reciprocal relationship as follows: ‘These capabilities can be enhanced by public policy, but also, on the other side, the direction of public policy can be influenced by the effective use of partici- patory capabilities by the public’: Development as Freedom (note 3 above) 18. 6 Jennifer Nedelsky describes human beings ‘as both essentially individual and essentially social creatures’: ‘Reconceiving Rights as Relationship’ (1993) 1 Review of Constitutional Studies 1, 8. In National Coalition for Gay & Lesbian Equality v Minister of Justice and Others 1999 (1) SA 6 (CC), Sachs J refers to the con- stitutional recognition of the associational dimensions of human life as follows: ‘While recognising the unique worth of each person, the Constitution does not presuppose that a holder of rights is an isolated, lonely and abstract figure possessing a disembodied and socially disconnected self. It acknowledges that people live in their bodies, their communities, their cultures, their places and their times’ (at para 117). See also Bernstein v Bester 1996 (2) SA 751 (CC) at para 67. 7 In Dawood v Minister of Home Affairs; Shalabi v Minister of Home Affairs; Thomas v Minister of Home Affairs 2000 (3) SA 936 (CC), O’Regan J describes the role of the constitutional value of human dignity in Human dignity as a right and value has played a central role in the Court’s human rights jurisprudence.8 The Court has also invoked dignity as the central value informing its approach to the interpretation of socio-economic rights, particularly the reasonableness standard of review for the positive duties imposed by these rights.9 Thus Yacoob J stated in Groot- boom: …It is fundamental to an evaluation of the reasonableness of State action that account be taken of the inherent dignity of human beings. The Constitution will be worth infinitely less than its paper if the reasonableness of State action concerned with housing is determined without regard to the fundamental constitutional value of human dignity. Section 26, read in the context of the Bill of Rights as a whole, must mean that the respondents have a right to reasonable action by the State in all circumstances and with particular regard to human dignity. In short, I emphasise that human beings are required to be treated as human beings…10 This article explores the value of human dignity in interpreting socio-economic rights.11 My focus is primarily on the positive duties imposed on these rights to facilitate and provide access to social benefits.12 It examines the critiques that have been made of human dignity as a guiding value in the context of South Africa’s equality jurisprudence. In response to these critiques the article seeks to explore traditions in the interpretation of human dignity that can make a positive contribution to our evolving jurisprudence on socio-economic rights. By focusing on human dignity, I am not claiming that dignity is the only value that explicates Human Dignity in Interpreting Socio-Economic Rights 143 constituting post-apartheid society: ‘The Constitution asserts dignity to contradict our past in which human dignity for black South Africans was routinely and cruelly denied. It asserts it too to inform the future, to invest in our democracy respect for the intrinsic worth of all human beings’ (at para 35). 8 In Dawood v Minister of Home Affairs; Shalabi v Minister of Home Affairs; Thomas v Minister of Home Affairs 2000 (3) SA 936 (CC) the Court held that the value of human dignity ‘is a value that informs the interpretation of many, possibly all, other rights’ (at para 35). See, for example, S v Makwanyane & Another 1995 (3) SA 391 (CC) at para 144 (per Chaskalson P) and at para 328 (per O’Regan J) (death penalty); August and Another v Electoral Commission and Others 1999 (3) SA 1 (CC) para 16 (per Sachs J) (right to vote); and the range of equality cases in which dignity is a central factor in identifying ‘unfair’ discrimination: eg Harksen v Lane NO and Others 1998 (1) SA 300 (CC) at paras 50 – 51; National Coalition for Gay & Lesbian Equality v Minister of Justice and Others 1999 (1) SA 6 (CC) at paras 15 – 28 (per Ackermann J), and paras 120 – 129 (per Sachs J). 9 Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC) paras 38, 41. 10 Note 9 above, para 83. On the relationship between human dignity as an independent right, the other rights specifically entrenched in the Bill of Rights, and the value of human dignity, see Dawood v Minister of Home Affairs; Shalabi v Minister of Home Affairs; Thomas v Minister of Home Affairs 2000 (3) SA 936 (CC) para 35. 11 On the relationship between human dignity as an independent right, the other rights specifically entrenched in the Bill of Rights, and the value of human dignity, see Dawood v Minister of Home Affairs; Shalabi v Minister of Home Affairs; Thomas v Minister of Home Affairs 2000 (3) SA 936 (CC) para 35; Jaftha v Schoeman and Others; Van Rooyen v Stoltz and Others 2005 (1) BCLR 78 (CC) para 21. 12 Section 7(2) of the Constitution places an overarching duty on the State ‘to respect, protect, promote and fulfil’ the rights in the Bill of Rights. This signals that the rights in the Bill of Rights impose a combination of negative and positive duties. For a discussion of these duties in the context of socio-economic rights, see S Liebenberg ‘The Interpretation of Socio-Economic Rights’ in M Chaskalson et al Constitutional Law of South Africa (2nd edition 2004) ch 33, 6 - 7; see also The Social and Economic Rights Action Centre and the Centre for Economic and Social Rights v Nigeria Communication No 155/96 October 2001, African Commission on Human and Peoples’ Rights, paras 44 – 47. 1 4 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E our commitment to socio-economic rights.13 There is an important body of literature that explores the significance of a number of other values in relation to socio-economic rights.14 The core foundational values of human dignity, freedom and equality are in any event highly inter- related.15 I focus on human dignity because of the important role it has played in the Court’s human rights jurisprudence in general, and because its role in the interpretation of socio-eco- nomic rights has been relatively unexplored. I also seek to develop a concept of human dignity that can help us identify deficiencies in the Court’s current socio-economic rights jurisprudence and illuminate how the jurisprudence should be developed to constitute a stronger response to socio-economic deprivation. II Critiques of Dignity as a Value in Constitutional Adjudication A number of critiques have been made of human dignity as a guiding value in constitutional adjudication, particularly in relation to equality jurisprudence and the test for unfair dis- crimination.16 However, these critiques are also relevant to human dignity as a guiding value in socio-economic rights jurisprudence and for this reason they require careful consideration here. Three major critiques of dignity as a value in human rights adjudication have been articulated. The first relates to the alleged indeterminacy of human dignity as a normative concept. Thus it has been argued that dignity is too vague and multifaceted a concept to serve us well as a guiding 13 The Court has affirmed that all three foundational constitutional values are implicated in a denial of socio- economic rights: ‘All the rights in our Bill of Rights are inter-related and mutually supporting. There can be no doubt that human dignity, freedom and equality, the foundational values of our society, are denied those who have no food, clothing or shelter. Affording socio-economic rights to all people therefore enables them to enjoy the other rights enshrined in Chapter 2. The realisation of these rights is also key to the advance- ment of race and gender equality and the evolution of a society in which men and women are equally able to achieve their full potential’: Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC) para 23. See also Soobramoney v Minister of Health, KwaZulu-Natal 1998 (1) SA 765 (CC) para 8. 14 See, for example, N Haysom ‘Constitutionalism, Majoritarian Democracy and Socio-Economic Rights’ (1992) 2 SAJHR 451 (a basic floor of socio-economic rights is required to guarantee a minimum degree of civic and political participation). For a similar argument in the US context, see: FI Michelman ‘Welfare Rights in a Constitutional Democracy’ (1979) 3 Wash Univ LQ 659 (socio-economic are necessary prereq- uisites of effective participation in representative democracy); P de Vos ‘Grootboom, The Right of Access to Housing and Substantive Equality as Contextual Fairness’ (2001) 17 SAJHR 258 (the right to equality and socio-economic rights are ‘two sides of the same coin’ in that they seek to achieve ‘…a specific con- textual form of equality as the realisation of particular social and economic rights’ at 263, 265). For a dis- cussion of the shortcomings and theoretical limitations of an equality-based theoretical justification of socio-economic rights: see A van der Walt ‘A South African Reading of Frank Michelman’s Theory of Social Justice’ in H Botha, A van der Walt, and J van der Walt (eds) Rights and Democracy in a Transformative Constitution (2004) 163 at 174 – 179. Nonetheless, as this paper illustrates, there are important insights in equality jurisprudence regarding the application of human dignity to adjudicate the constitutionality of peo- ple’s exclusion from social benefits. 15 Kriegler J refers to human dignity, equality and freedom as ‘conjoined, reciprocal and covalent values’ which are ‘foundational’ to South Africa: S v Mamabolo (E TV and Others Intervening) 2001 (3) SA 409 (CC) at para 41. 16 The Court’s approach to section 9 of the Constitution is set out in Harksen v Lane NO and Others 1998 (1) SA 300 (CC) at paras 50 – 53. Dignity plays an important role both in the identification of unlisted pro- hibited grounds of discrimination and in the factors for determining whether the discrimination is unfair: see Harksen paras 49 and 51. value in equality jurisprudence.17 The second critique asserts that human dignity as a value is irrevocably linked with protection of freedom and autonomy. As such, it serves to discourage the positive, redistributive measures needed to remedy conditions of material inequality and disad- vantage.18 Cathi Albertyn and Beth Goldblatt have most forcefully articulated the final critique (which is closely related to the second) in the context of equality jurisprudence. They argue that the reliance on the value of dignity in the test for unfair discrimination promotes a narrow focus on individual personality issues as opposed to ‘a group-based understanding of material advan- tage and disadvantage’.19 It could result in ‘an individualised and abstract conception of equality divorced from actual social and economic disadvantage.’20 Thus the need to redress systemic pat- terns of inequality and disadvantage are obscured by focusing on individual personality issues related to subjective feelings of self-respect and self-worth. If dignity as a value is inextricably aligned with negative liberty and individual personality issues, it will be inimical to the development of a transformative socio-economic rights jurispru- dence. In the next section I develop an argument that there are positive traditions associated with the interpretation of human dignity that can add value to our socio-economic rights jurisprudence. In so doing, I am not seeking to deny the dangers of a regressive deployment of human dignity in the interpretation of rights such as equality, and indeed, socio-economic rights. Certainly, I believe that there is a case to be made that the Court has not engaged suffi- ciently with the value of equality in its section 9 jurisprudence.21 My concern is to examine how the value of human dignity can enrich, rather than impoverish, our evolving jurisprudence on socio-economic rights. III Human Dignity as a Value Dignity has deep roots in Kantian moral philosophy that affirms the inherent worth of human beings. According to the Kantian imperative human beings should be treated ‘never simply as a Human Dignity in Interpreting Socio-Economic Rights 145 17 For example, Davis alludes to the ‘multifaceted meanings’ of dignity, and argues that the Court ‘has given dignity both a content and scope that make for a piece of jurisprudential Legoland – to be used in whatev- er form and shape is required by the demands of the judicial designer’: D Davis ‘Equality: The Majesty of Legoland Jurisprudence’ (1999) 116 SALJ 398 at 413. See also in this regard D Davis Democracy and Deliberation (1999) at 69 – 95. 18 This critique is discussed by Susie Cowen in her article defending the use of the value of human dignity in South African’s equality jurisprudence: ‘Can “Dignity” Guide South Africa’s Equality Jurisprudence?’ (2001) 17 SAJHR 34 at 51 – 58. 19 C Albertyn & B Goldblatt ‘Facing the Challenge of Transformation: Difficulties in the Development of an Indigenous Jurisprudence of Equality’ (1998) 14 SAJHR 248 at 257 – 258, 272. Similar arguments in sup- port of the development of a more substantive approach to equality were made by the Centre for Applied Legal Studies in their amicus intervention in National Coalition for Gay & Lesbian Equality v Minister of Justice and Others 1999 (1) SA 6 (CC): see paras 58 – 64 (per Ackermann J), and paras 120 – 129 (per Sachs J). 20 C Albertyn ‘Equality’ in M H Cheadle, D M Davis and N R L Haysom (eds) South African Constitutional Law: The Bill of Rights (2002) 51 at 60. 21 Albertyn attributes this reluctance, at least partially, to the Court’s discomfort with the notion that ‘the value of equality encompasses an idea of material equality and economic redistribution’: She argues that this ‘redistributive function sits uncomfortably with the institutional role of courts and with the distinction the courts seek to draw between issues of social policy and issues of law’: Albertyn (note 20 above) at 63 – 65; See also D Davis ‘Legoland Jurisprudence’ (note 17 above) at 413 – 414. For a recent consideration by the Court of the value of equality in the context of section 9 and the positive duties it imposes on the state, see Minister of Finance & Another v Van Heerden 2004 (11) BCLR 1125 (CC) at paras 22 – 27. 1 4 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E means, but always at the same time as an end.’22 In other words, we should relate to each other as having intrinsic worth as human beings. O’Regan J affirms the notion of human dignity as follows: …The importance of dignity as a founding value of our new Constitution cannot be over-emphasised. Recognising a right to dignity is an acknowledgment of the intrin- sic worth of human beings: human beings are entitled to be treated as worthy of respect and concern…23 Human dignity is closely related to the notion that human beings are agents capable of making moral choices, of shaping our identity, resisting injustice and participating in the shaping of society.24 Martha Nussbaum expresses this notion thus: The core idea is that of the human being as a dignified free being who shapes his or her own life in cooperation and reciprocity with others, rather than being passively shaped or pushed around by the world in the manner of a “flock” or “herd” animal. A life that is really human is one that is shaped throughout by these human powers of practical reason and sociability.25 Thus to value the inherent dignity of human beings as a society is to ensure that people enjoy 22 I Kant The Moral Law: Kant’s Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals (1963) (trans H J Patron) 96 cited and discussed in D Meyerson Rights Limited (1997) at 12 – 13. See also the discussion of the Kantian imperative and concept of human dignity by L Ackermann ‘Equality and the South African Constitution: The Role of Dignity’ (2000) 60 The Heidelberg Journal for International Law 537 at 540 – 542. 23 S v Makwanyane & Another 1995 (3) SA 391 (CC) para 328 (emphasis added). See also the comments of Ackermann J in National Coalition for Gay & Lesbian Equality v Minister of Justice and Others 1999 (1) SA 6 (CC): ‘Dignity is a difficult concept to capture in precise terms. At its least, it is clear that the consti- tutional protection of dignity requires us to acknowledge the value and worth of all individuals as members of society’ (at para 29). 24 In the context of evictions, the Constitutional Court has recently highlighted the importance of mediation and serious consideration of the need of occupiers for suitable alternative land in considering whether an eviction is ‘just and equitable’ in terms of The Prevention of Illegal Eviction from and Unlawful Occupation of Land Act 19 of 1998 (PIE). Sachs J refers to the importance of mutual respect for people’s agency in the following terms: ‘Thus those seeking eviction should not be encouraged to rely on concepts of faceless and anonymous squatters automatically to be expelled as obnoxious social nuisances. Such a stereotypical approach has no place in the society envisaged by the Constitution; justice and equity require that everyone is to be treated as an individual bearer of rights entitled to respect for his or her dignity. At the same time those who find themselves compelled by poverty and landlessness to live in shacks on the land of others, should be discouraged from regarding themselves as helpless victims, lacking the possibility of personal moral agency’: Port Elizabeth Municipality v Various Occupiers 2005 (1) SA 217 (CC) para 41. 25 M Nussbaum Women and Human Development (note 3 above) 72 (footnotes omitted). Nussbaum’s notion of ‘a life that is really human’ has been the subject of criticism on the basis that that an attempt to elabo- rate the conditions of a fully human life implies that those who are denied these conditions have lost their dignity and are no longer ‘dignified’: see D Cornell ‘A Call for a Nuanced Constitutional Jurisprudence: Ubuntu, Dignity, and Reconciliation’ paper presented at a New Social Forms Seminar organised by the Department of Sociology and Social Anthropology, Stellenbosch University, 23 July 2004 (paper on line at www.sun.ac.za/sociology/activities_nsf.htm). My own reading of Nussbaum is that she is not claiming that poverty deprives people of their dignity, but rather that society fails to respect the dignity of people by neglecting to create the conditions under which people’s capabilities can develop and be effectively exer- cised. As she puts it: ‘We begin, then, with a sense of the worth and dignity of basic human powers, think- ing of them as claims to a chance for functioning, claims that give rise to correlated social and political duties’: Women and Human Development (note 3 above) 84. See further the discussion at 84 – 86. civil and political liberties and also have effective access to the social and economic means indis- pensable to the development of their physical, emotional, creative and associational capabili- ties. Nussbaum develops a provisional list of ‘central human capabilities’ that should be secured as a basic social minimum to all in political and constitutional principles. Through this list she seeks to isolate ‘those human capabilities that can be convincingly argued to be of central importance in any human life, whatever else the person pursues or chooses.’26 She argues that that they have ‘special claim to be supported for political purposes in a pluralistic society’ because of their importance in making any choice of a way of life possible.’27 Nussbaum’s proj- ect of developing a list of ‘central human capabilities’ has been criticised for being reductive and insufficiently sensitive to human difference, complexity and freedom.28 A valuable feature of the list is its holistic portrayal of human life. It illustrates that access to socio-economic rights is not simply a matter of bare survival, but also includes the development and exercise of the people’s associational, intellectual and emotional capabilities. In any event, I do not believe that it is necessary to subscribe to her list (or even her project of compiling a list) to support the cen- tral idea that we show respect for human potential and agency by creating an environment of basic liberties and material support which enables their flourishing.29 In his analysis of human dignity as a normative concept, Oscar Schachter distinguishes between ‘the subjective aspect of human dignity (how one feels or thinks about another) and the objective aspect (how one treats another)’.30 In its objective, social dimension, he argues that human dignity ‘requires recognition of a minimal concept of distributive justice that would require satisfaction of the essential needs of everyone.’31 Thus he includes in his list of conduct and ideas that offend or denigrate the worth and dignity of individuals, ‘[d]egrading living conditions and deprivation of basic needs.’32 International human rights law derives civil and political rights as well as social, economic and cultural rights from the value of human Human Dignity in Interpreting Socio-Economic Rights 147 26 Nussbaum Women and Human Development (note 3 above) 74. Her list of central human functional capa- bilities relates to the following dimensions of human existence: life; health; bodily integrity; the senses, imagination and thought; emotions, practical reason, affiliation; other species; play; political and material control over one’s environment (at 77 – 80). 27 Nussbaum Women and Human Development (note 3 above) 75. 28 See K Van Marle ‘“The Capabilities Approach”, “The Imaginary Domain”, and “Asymmetrical Reciprocity”: Feminist Perspectives on Equality and Justice’ (2003) 11 Feminist Legal Studies 255 – 278, particularly the discussion at 272 – 273. Sen’s reservations regarding the search for a list of central human capabilities relates to the difficulty ‘in seeing how the exact lists and weights would be chosen without appropriate specification of the context of their use (which could vary), but also from a disinclination to accept any substantive diminution of the domain of public reasoning’: For Sen the framework of human capabilities is important for clarifying and illuminating ‘the subject matter of public reasoning…It does not – and cannot – displace the need for public reasoning’: A Sen ‘Elements of a Theory of Human Rights’ (2004) 32 Philosophy and Public Affairs 315 – 356 at 333. 29 Nussbaum herself emphasises that the list ‘remains open-ended and humble; it can always be contested and remade’. It aims at ‘multiple realisability’, leaving room for more concrete specification according to local beliefs and circumstances: Women and Human Development (note 3 above) 77. 30 O Schachter ‘Human Dignity as a Normative Concept’ (1983) 77 Am J of Int Law 848, 849. 31 Schachter (note 30 above) 851. David Feldman makes the following observations in relation to the subjec- tive and objective dimensions of human dignity: ‘In relation to the subjective aspect of dignity, the law of human rights will typically be concerned to prevent treatment which damages a person’s self-respect and physical or moral integrity. With regard to the objective aspect, the law will usually have to go further, imposing positive duties on people to act in ways which optimise the conditions for social respect and dig- nity’: ‘Human Dignity as a Value – Part I’ (1999) 14 Public Law 682 at 686 – 687. 32 Schachter (note 30 above) 852. 1 4 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E dignity.33 The Constitutional Court has also on a number of occasions referred to the dis- juncture between our founding constitutional values and conditions of material deprivation.34 The above approaches to human dignity illustrate that its ambit is by no means confined to sub- jective personality issues. To the contrary, respect for human dignity requires that we pay close attention to conditions of material disadvantage and its impact on different groups in our society. This brings us to the concern that human dignity is irrevocably connected with negative lib- erty. Accordingly, dignity as a value would support constraints on State interference with indi- vidual liberties, and would discourage intervention to redistribute social resources. Human dig- nity undeniably requires respect for personal autonomy and choices.35 But at the same time our commitment to respect for each person’s substantive freedom and life choices requires the cre- ation of the social conditions on which people’s capacity for personal fulfilment and agency depends. This leads David Feldman to describe dignity as a ‘two-edged sword’, which can oper- ate both to uphold and restrict personal liberties: …[W]e must not assume that the idea of dignity is inextricably linked to a liberal- individualistic view of human beings whose life-choices deserve respect. If the state takes a particular view of what is required for people to live dignified lives, it may introduce regulations to restrict the freedom which people have to make choices which, in the state’s view interfere with the dignity of the individual, a social group or the human race as a whole. …The quest for human dignity may subvert rather than enhance choice and in some circumstances may limit rather than extend the scope of traditional ‘first generation’ human rights and fundamental freedoms…36 33 The preambles of both the International Covenant on Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights (1966) and the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (1966) recognise that the rights contained in the respective Covenants ‘derive from the inherent dignity of the human person’: In The Social and Economic Rights Action Center and the Center for Economic and Social Rights v Nigeria (note 12 above), the African Commission on Human and Peoples’ Rights derived the right to food from a number of other provisions in the African Charter on Human and Peoples’ Rights. In particular, it held that the right to food ‘is insepa- rably linked to the dignity of human beings and is therefore essential for the enjoyment and fulfilment of other rights as health, education, work and political participation’ (at para 65). 34 In Soobramoney v Minister of Health, KwaZulu-Natal 1998 (1) SA 765 (CC), the Court affirmed that the Constitution commits us to transform the intolerable conditions in which people live in order to vindicate the values of human dignity, equality and freedom: paras 8 – 10. In Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC) the Court stated that the issues in the case remind us of the intol- erable conditions under which many of our people are still living and brings home ‘the harsh reality that the Constitution’s promise of dignity and equality for all remains a distant dream’: (para 2). See also A Chaskalson (The Third Bram Fischer Lecture) ‘Human Dignity as a Foundational Value of our Constitutional Order’ (2000) 16 SAJHR 193 at 204 – 205. 35 The links between dignity and freedom are described in the following terms by Ackermann J in Ferreira v Levin NO 1996 (1) SA 984 (CC): ‘Human dignity cannot be fully valued or respected unless individuals are able to devel- op their humanity, their “humanness” to the full extent of its potential. Each human being is uniquely talented. Part of the dignity of every human being is the fact and awareness of this uniqueness. An individual’s human dig- nity cannot be fully respected or valued unless the individual is permitted to develop his or her talents optimally. Human dignity has little value without freedom; for without freedom personal development and fulfilment are not possible. Without freedom, human dignity is little more than an abstraction. Freedom and dignity are inseparably linked. To deny people their freedom is to deny them their dignity’: (at para 49). See also Prince v President of the Law Society of the Cape of Good Hope & Others 2002 (2) SA 794 (CC): ‘Our society is diverse…The protection of diversity is the hallmark of a free and open society. It is the recognition of the inherent dignity of all human beings. Freedom is an indispensable ingredient of human dignity’: (per Ngcobo J at para 49). 36 D Feldman (note 31 above) 685. This may suggest that dignity is an indeterminate value – it cannot guide us as to when con- straints should be placed on State interference with liberties and when it should require posi- tive intervention. The capabilities approach to human dignity developed by Nussbaum provides us with at least one set of criteria for requiring positive state intervention. In Nussbaum’s account, the State has a strong duty to guarantee the social basis of each person’s basic human capabilities based on a principle of each person as an end.37 This fundamental commitment necessarily implies that the State is entitled to restrict the liberties of some members of society (provided it does not impinge on their basic human capabilities) in order to guarantee to every- one the social basis of basic human capabilities.38 In this sense a focus on capabilities as social goals is also closely related to human equality. As Nussbaum explains: …[M]aking capabilities the goal entails promoting for all citizens a greater measure of material equality than exists in most societies, since we are unlikely to get all cit- izens above a minimum threshold of capability for truly human functioning without some redistributive policies…39 Nussbaum’s approach is compatible with a range of different theories as to the degree of mate- rial equality that should be guaranteed in a just society, including complete egalitarianism, a Rawlsian difference principle, and a focus on an ample social minimum for all.40 However, in most societies in the world, including South Africa, we are very far from providing even the basic minimum required for promoting human capabilities.41 It is also helpful in this context to conceive of human dignity as a relational value. According to this notion we are interconnected beings. Our sense of self-worth, personal development and well-being is inextricably bound up with the extent to which we are valued by others and the society at large. O’Regan J expresses this when she writes in Makwanyane: …the right to life was included in the Constitution not simply to enshrine the right to existence. It is not life as mere organic matter that the Constitution cherishes, but the right to human life: the right to live as a human being, to be part of a broader community, to share in the experience of humanity…The right to life is more than existence, it is a right to be treated as a human being with dignity… .42 Human Dignity in Interpreting Socio-Economic Rights 149 37 M Nussbaum Women and Human Development (note 3 above) at 5 – 6, 89. In certain core areas of human functioning, ‘a necessary condition of justice for a public political arrangement is that it delivers to citizens a certain basic level of capability’: (at 71). She draws a distinction between capability and functioning, defending the former as the appropriate political goal given the value we attach to respecting people’s choices. It is not the role of government to push people into ‘functioning of the requisite sort’: (at 87). She argues that ‘for political purposes it is appropriate that we shoot for capabilities and those alone. Citizens must be left free to determine their own course after that. The person with plenty of food may always choose to fast, but there is a great dif- ference between fasting and starving, and it is this difference that I wish to capture’: (at 87). 38 In discussing socio-economic rights such as the right to shelter in terms of her capabilities approach, Nussbaum identifies the central focus to be ‘how people are actually enabled to live’: ‘Analyzing economic and material rights in terms of capabilities thus enables us to set forth clearly a rationale we have for spend- ing unequal amounts of money on the disadvantaged, or creating special programs to assist their transition to full capability’: Women and Human Development (note 3 above) 99. 39 Nussbaum Women and Human Development (note 3 above) 86. 40 Ibid. 41 See further in this regard Women and Human Development (note 3 above) 12, 86. 42 S v Makwanyane & Another 1995 (3) SA 391 (CC) paras 326 –7. In Soobramoney v Minister of Health, KwaZulu-Natal 1998 (1) SA 765 (CC) the Court affirmed that having access to social goods and services 1 5 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E To value human dignity is not to create zero-sum trade-offs between negative liberty and wel- fare, but to constitute positive social relationships that both respect autonomy and foster the conditions in which it can flourish.43 Dignity as a relational value can help us to perceive the limits of individual claims on social resources with reference to the needs and equal worth of others and the available resources of the society.44 But the corollary is a collective acknowledge- ment we are diminished as a society to the extent that any of our members are deprived of the opportunities to develop their basic capabilities to function as individual and social beings.45 Mokgoro J expresses this idea in the following passage in the case of Khosa v Minister of Social Development: …Sharing responsibility for the problems and consequences of poverty equally as a community represents the extent to which wealthier members of the community view the minimal well-being of the poor as connected with their personal well-being and were aspects of the right to ‘…human life: the right to live as a human being, to be part of a broader communi- ty to share in the experience of humanity’: (at para 31). The associational dimensions of human dignity were also recently affirmed by the Supreme Court of Appeal in the decision of Minister of Home Affairs and Others v Watchenuka and Another 2004 (2) BCLR 120 (SCA). The Court held that conditions imposed on refugees and asylum-seekers prohibiting them from undertaking employment and from studying constituted an infringement of their rights to human dignity and education. The Court (per Nugent JA) stated: ‘The freedom to engage in pro- ductive work – even where that is not required in order to survive – is indeed an important component of human dignity…for mankind is pre-eminently a social species with an instinct for meaningful association. Self-esteem and the sense of self-worth – the fulfilment of what it is to be human – is most often bound up with being accept- ed as socially useful’: (para 27). It is important, however, not to associate the right to work only with productive, waged work. One of the major contributing factors to gender inequality is society’s persistent undervaluing of reproductive work of which women bear the disproportionate burden. See in this regard, President of the Republic of South African and Another v Hugo 1997 (4) SA 1 (CC) at para 38 (per Goldstone J). 43 The relational conception of autonomy is described in the following terms by Jennifer Nedelsky: ‘Interdependence becomes the central fact of political life, not an issue to be shunted to the periphery in the basic question of how to ensure individual autonomy in the inevitable face of collective power. The human interactions to be governed are not seen primarily in terms of the clashing of rights and interests, but in terms of the way patterns of rela- tionship can develop and sustain both an enriching collective life and the scope for genuine individual autono- my…The constitutional protection of autonomy is then no longer an effort to carve out a space into which the collective cannot intrude, but a means of structuring the relations between individuals and the sources of collec- tive power so that autonomy is fostered rather than undermined’: (note 6 above) 8. In the South African context, the interdependence between individual and community is captured by the spirit of ubuntu. Mokgoro J explains that while ‘ubuntu envelops the key values of group solidarity, compassion, respect, human dignity, conformity to basic norms and collective unity, in its fundamental sense it denotes humanity and morality. Its spirit empha- sises a respect for human dignity, marking a shift from confrontation to conciliation’: S v Makwanyane & Another 1995 (3) SA 391 (CC) para 308 (per Mokgoro J). In Port Elizabeth Municipality v Various Occupiers 2005 (1) SA 217 (CC) the Court (per Sachs J) further noted: ‘The spirit of ubuntu, part of the deep cultural her- itage of the majority of the population, suffuses the whole constitutional order. It combines individual rights with a communitarian philosophy. It is a unifying motif of the Bill of Rights, which is nothing if not a structured, insti- tutionalised and operational declaration in our evolving new society of the need for human interdependence, respect and concern’: (para 37, footnotes omitted). 44 In Soobramoney v Minister of Health, KwaZulu-Natal 1998 (1) SA 765 (CC) the Court justified the limi- tation of the appellant’s right to tertiary-level health care services by referring to the State’s duty to manage its resources so as to meet the basic needs of others: paras 28, 31 (per Chaskalson P), and para 54 (per Sachs J). See, however, the critique of Soobramoney in Karin van Marle ‘”No Last Word” – Reflections on the Imaginary Domain, Dignity and Intrinsic Worth’ (2002) Stell LR 299, particularly at 305 – 307. 45 In an article on the application of the value of human dignity in criminal law, Shannon Hoctor argues that ‘dignity has a communitarian aspect: by requiring respect for others’ claims to dignity, vindication of the human dignity of all is better assured, and a community of mutual co-operation and solidarity is fostered’: ‘Dignity, Criminal Law and the Bill of Rights’ (2004) 121 SALJ 265 at 315 (footnotes omitted). the well-being of the community as a whole. In other words, decisions about the allo- cation of public benefits represent the extent to which poor people are treated as equal members of society…46 It is implicit in a relational concept of dignity that claims on social resources are strongly justi- fied when people lack the basic material necessities of life to enable them to survive and devel- op as members of the community. If we are to constitute ourselves as a society that respects human dignity (as we have through the founding values of our Constitution), we are commit- ted to redressing the social and economic conditions of those whose capacity for development and agency is stunted by poverty. By failing to do so, we undermine the very foundations of our new constitutional democracy.47 The decision in Minister of Health v Treatment Action Campaign48 (hereafter ‘TAC’) illustrates the underlying relational concept of human dignity at work. The government was being asked to provide a relatively cheap anti-retroviral drug (Nevirapine)49 with a significant potential of reduc- ing the risk of mother-to-child transmission of HIV.50 While there were additional costs associat- ed with prescribing the drug, particularly the costs of HIV-testing and counselling facilities, the Court found that government had the resources to extend these facilities to hospitals and clinics throughout the public health sector beyond the limited number of test sites.51 For the babies of poor women who give birth in the public health sector, this drug has significant life-saving poten- tial. For society to deny poor women and their newborns access to ‘a simple, cheap and poten- tially lifesaving medical intervention’52 would clearly indicate a lack of respect for their dignity as human beings entitled to be treated as worthy of respect and concern. I have sought to illustrate that human dignity derives from the value we ascribe to human beings. Because we value them, we wish to ensure that conditions are created that enable them to develop their capabilities and to flourish as individual and social beings. This encompasses respect for people’s diverse identities, their associational freedoms, as well as concern for the material conditions that shape their life choices. Dignity as a value requires respect for people’s freedoms, but also helps us to understand why these liberties must sometimes be constrained to protect and nurture the capabilities of others. Finally, I have argued that a relational concept of human dignity best captures the interdependence between individual and social welfare, and Human Dignity in Interpreting Socio-Economic Rights 151 46 Khosa & Others v Minister of Social Development and Others; Mahlaule and Another v Minister of Social Development and Others 2004 (6) BCLR 569 (CC) para 74 (footnotes omitted). 47 In the context of unfair discrimination, the Court has held that ‘the interests of the community lie in the recognition of the inherent dignity of every human being and the elimination of all forms of discrimination’: Hoffman v SAA 2000 (11) BCLR 1211 (CC) at para 43. In the context of evictions of poor people from their homes, the Court has stated: ‘It is not only the dignity of the poor that is assailed when homeless peo- ple are driven from pillar to post in a desperate quest for a place where they and their families can rest their heads. Our society as a whole is demeaned when state action intensifies rather than mitigates their margin- alisation. The integrity of the rights-based vision of the Constitution is punctured when governmental action augments rather than reduces denial of the claims of the desperately poor to the basic elements of a decent existence. Hence the need for special judicial control of a process that is both socially stressful and potentially conflictual’: Port Elizabeth Municipality v Various Occupiers 2005 (1) SA 217 (CC) para 18. 48 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC). 49 The manufacturers of Nevirapine had offered to make it available to the South African government free of charge for a period of five years, for the purpose of reducing the risk of mother-to-child transmission of HIV. Minister of Health v Treatment Action Campaign (2) 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC) para 19 read with paras 71 and 80. 50 Para 57. 51 Paras 118 – 120. 52 Para 73. 1 5 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E also illuminates the circumstances in which people have justified claims to social resources. In the next section I examine how the value of human dignity can be applied to enrich South Africa’s socio-economic rights jurisprudence. I also examine, through my discussion of the Canadian case of Gosselin,53 applications of human dignity that can operate to exclude the poor from access to benefits, rather than facilitate their inclusion. IV Human Dignity and its Value in Socio-Economic Rights Jurisprudence I have argued for a relational concept of human dignity in which society’s neglect to redress condi- tions of socio-economic disadvantage represents a collective failure to value human dignity. This con- cept helps to challenge stigmatizing notions of the poor as ‘dependants’ of society and undeserving of social support.54 Conditions of poverty are not a reflection of the moral blameworthiness of groups experiencing poverty;55 they reflect how we as a society have failed to value human dignity. There is another dimension of human dignity that can make an important contribution to the development of our socio-economic rights jurisprudence. This is the concept of the equal worth of people that lies at the heart of human dignity. As the Court has affirmed in the con- text of its equality jurisprudence, the acknowledgment of equal moral worth requires treatment as an equal as opposed to equal treatment.56 Treatment as an equal requires full acknowledge- ment of the racial, gender, social, economic, cultural and other differences between groups in society. Thus the quest for equal worth or dignity is not a quest for uniformity, but a quest to eliminate the disadvantages and inferior status that attach to membership of particular groups.57 This substantive approach to equality inevitably requires a contextual analysis which is able to identify the real situations and disadvantages experienced by various groups in the light of our history as well as current social, economic, political and gender relations.58 Treatment as an equal demands that we also respond appropriately to the actual needs of dif- 53 Gosselin v Quebec (Attorney General), 2002 SCC 84, 221 DLR (4th) 257. 54 The Court has affirmed the close relationship between human dignity and social assistance in the cases of Khosa & Others v Minister of Social Development and Others; Mahlaule and Another v Minister of Social Development and Others 2004 (6) BCLR 569 (CC) paras 41 and 52 and Mashavha v President of the RSA & Others 2004 (12) BCLR 1243 (CC) para 51. 55 On approaches to adjudication in the US premised on notions of the moral blameworthiness of the poor, and the attitude of ‘helplessness’ in response to their claims, see T Ross ‘The Rhetoric of Poverty: Their Immorality, Our Helplessness’ (1991) 79 Georgetown Law Journal 1499 – 1547. 56 See R Dworkin Taking Rights Seriously (1977) at 227 cited in Prinsloo v Van der Linde 1997 (3) SA 1012 (CC) at para 32. 57 As Sachs J states in National Coalition for Gay & Lesbian Equality v Minister of Justice and Others 1999 (1) SA 6 (CC): ‘At the heart of the equality jurisprudence is the rescuing of people from a caste-like status and putting an end to their being treated as lesser human beings because they belong to a particular group. The indignity and subordinate status may flow from institutionally imposed exclusion from the mainstream of society or else from powerlessness within the mainstream…’ (para 129). He goes on to affirm that ‘[e]quality means equal concern and respect across difference’ as opposed to uniformity which ‘can be the enemy of equality’: (para 132). 58 In Brink v Kitshoff NO 1996 (4) SA 197 (CC) O’Regan J refers to the ‘deep patterns of disadvantage’ which have resulted from gender discrimination in our society, particularly in the case of black women. A ‘key message of the Constitution’ is that ‘all such discrimination needs to be eradicated from our society’: (para 44). In its socio-economic rights jurisprudence, the Court has also indicated the reasonableness of the State’s measures to realise socio-economic rights must be evaluated in the light of their ‘social, economic and his- torical context’: Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC) para 43. ferently situated groups. In Harksen v Lane NO, O’Regan J (in her dissenting judgment) affirms that respect for human dignity in equality jurisprudence requires an approach that is responsive to individual needs and circumstances in order to create a buffer against the con- struction of further patterns of discrimination: …Such patterns of discrimination can occur where people are treated without the respect that individual human beings deserve and particularly where treatment is determined not by the needs or circumstances of particular individuals, but by their attributes and characteristics, whether biologically or socially determined…59 Building on this concept of human dignity in equality jurisprudence, dignity as a value in socio- economic rights jurisprudence requires that we take account of the relative urgency of the needs of different individuals and groups and respond correspondingly.60 This implies a contextual analysis with regard to the position of particular groups in society and the different orders and types of need experienced by these groups. Thus, for example, one would be required to con- sider the multifarious ways in which gender relations contribute to women’s unequal access to socio-economic resources.61 One would also have to consider the nature of the deprivation and the seriousness of its impact upon the affected individuals. In Watchenuka’s case, the Supreme Court of Appeal held that a consideration of the severe impact of an administrative decision on the socio-economic circumstances of the applicants was a highly relevant factor.62 Thus, while the State could justifiably limit the rights of non-nation- als (such as asylum-seekers) to undertake employment and education, different considerations applied when the applicants were destitute. When employment ‘is the only reasonable means for the person’s support’ what is then in issue ‘is not merely a restriction upon the person’s Human Dignity in Interpreting Socio-Economic Rights 153 59 Harksen v Lane NO and Others 1998 (1) SA 300 (CC) para 92 [emphasis added]. In Canadian equality jurisprudence, human dignity is also central to the determination of discrimination in terms of sec 15 of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms. In Law v Canada (Minister of Employment and Immigration) (1999) 170 DLR (4th) 1, [1999] 1 SCR 497 the Court developed the following understanding of what respect for human dignity in equality jurisprudence requires: ‘Human dignity means that an individual or group feels self-respect and self-worth. It is concerned with physical and psychological integrity and empowerment. Human dignity is harmed by unfair treatment premised upon personal traits or circum- stances which do not relate to individual needs, capacities or merits. It is enhanced by laws which are sen- sitive to the needs, capacities, and merits of different individuals, taking into account the context underly- ing their differences. Human dignity is harmed when individuals and groups are marginalized, ignored, or devalued, and is enhanced when laws recognise the full place of all individuals and groups within Canadian society.” (at para 53) [emphasis added]. In her dissenting judgment in Gosselin v Quebec (Attorney General) 2002 SCC 84, 221 DLR (4th) L’Heureux-Dubé J states: ‘Prejudicial effects giving rise to a s 15 claim may result when a legislature simply fails to turn its mind to the particular needs and abilities of indi- viduals or groups so as to provide equal benefit under the law to all members of society’: (at para 120). 60 See the discussion by Bilchitz of the concept of urgency in protecting people’s basic interest in survival and non-impaired functioning: D Bilchitz ‘Giving Socio-Economic Rights Teeth: The Minimum Core and its Importance’ (2002) 118 SALJ 484 at 490 – 491. 61 Martha Nussbaum argues for the importance of ‘an approach that is respectful of each person’s struggle for flourishing, that treats each person as an end and as a source of agency and worth in her own right’: (note 3 above) 69. She critiques utilitarian and resource-based approaches to human development as ‘insensitive to contextual variation, to the way circumstances shape preferences and the ability of individuals to con- vert resources into meaningful human activity’: (note 3 above) 69 - 70. Particularly in the developing world we need to be ‘highly alert’ to individual variations of need and the extent to which differently-situated indi- viduals can ‘convert resources into valuable functionings’: (note 3 above) 68. 62 Minister of Home Affairs and Others v Watchenuka and Another 2004 (2) BCLR 120 (SCA). 1 5 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E capacity for self-fulfilment, but a restriction upon his or her ability to live without positive humiliation of degradation.’63 To prohibit work and study in these circumstances would nor- mally be unlawful. This requires the Refugee Reception Offices and the Standing Committee on Refugee Affairs to carefully consider the impact of a restrictive condition regarding work or study on the individual applicant and his or her family. In its socio-economic rights jurisprudence the Court has affirmed that a reasonable gov- ernment policy must cater for different groups and orders of need in society.64 The Court has also taken the critical step of affirming that a government programme that neglects to attend to urgent needs cannot be reasonable. In Grootboom the government’s otherwise compre- hensive and rational housing programme65 was faulted for failing to cater for groups in urgent need: …To be reasonable, measures cannot leave out of account the degree and extent of the denial of the right they endeavour to realise. Those whose needs are most urgent and whose ability to enjoy all rights therefore is most in peril, must not be ignored by the measures aimed at achieving the realisation of the right. It may not be suffi- cient to meet the test of reasonableness to show that the measures are capable of achieving a statistical advance in the realisation of the right. Furthermore, the Constitution requires that everyone must be treated with care and concern. If the measures, though statistically successful, fail to respond to the needs of those most desperate, they may not pass the test…66 The Court has further acknowledged that ‘the poor are particularly vulnerable and their needs 63 Minister of Home Affairs and Others v Watchenuka and Another 2004 (2) BCLR 120 (SCA) para 32 (per Nugent JA). In relation to freedom of education Nugent JA held that when ‘a child is lawfully in this coun- try to seek asylum (there might be other circumstances as well) I can see no justification for limiting that right so as to deprive him or her of the opportunity for human fulfilment at a critical period…A general prohibition that does not allow for study to be permitted in appropriate circumstances is in my view unlaw- ful’: (at para 36) [footnotes omitted, emphasis added]. 64 Thus in Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC) the Court held that a reasonable programme ‘must be balanced and flexible and make appropriate provision for attention to housing crises and to short, medium and long-term needs. A programme that excludes a significant seg- ment of society cannot be said to be reasonable’: (para 43). 65 Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC) paras 53 – 54. 66 Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC) para 44 [emphasis added]. See also para 52: ‘[T]here is no express provision [in the Housing Act, 107 of 1997] to facilitate access to temporary relief for people who have no access to land, no roof over their heads, for people who are living in intolerable conditions and for people who are in crisis because of natural disasters such as floods and fire, or because their home homes are under threat of demolition. These are people in desperate need’: See also Minister of Health v Treatment Action Campaign 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC): ‘The provision of a single dose of Nevirapine to mother and child for the purpose of protecting the child against the transmission of HIV is, as far as the children are concerned, essential. Their needs are “most urgent” and their inability to have access to Nevirapine profoundly affects their ability to enjoy all rights to which they are entitled. Their rights are “most in peril” as a result of the policy that has been adopted and most affected by a rigid and inflexible policy that excludes them from having access to Nevirapine’: (para 78). In Port Elizabeth Municipality v Various Occupiers 2005 (1) SA 217 (CC), the Court emphasised the importance of taking account of ‘the actual situation’ of the persons concerned in eviction proceedings: ‘In a society founded on human dignity, equality and freedom it cannot be presupposed that the greatest good for the many can be achieved at the cost of intolerable hardship for the few, particularly if by a reasonable application of judi- cial and administrative statecraft such human distress could be avoided’: (para 29). require special attention.’67 Respect for human dignity requires society to marshal its resources and respond strongly to situations in which certain groups are unable to gain access to basic socio-economic needs. The consequences of the deprivation will be severe (either in terms of threats to life or health), and erode the foundations for the further development of people’s capabilities. To value human beings as a society demands an appropriate response. The overall resources and capacity of the society concerned will naturally determine this response. But dig- nity demands that society do its utmost to ensure that those groups who are unable to gain access to basic socio-economic needs are assisted.68 This duty is recognised by the United Nations Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights in interpreting States parties’ obligations under the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1966). According to the Committee, ‘…a State party in which any significant number of individuals is deprived of essential foodstuffs, of essential pri- mary health care, of basic shelter and housing, or of the most basic forms of education is, prima facie, failing to discharge its obligations under the Covenant.’ 69 This places a burden on the State, should it seek to attribute its failure to meet its core obligation to a lack of available resources, to ‘demonstrate that every effort has been made to use all resources that are at its disposal in an effort to satisfy, as a matter of priority, those minimum obligations.’ 70 In Grootboom and TAC, the Court rejected the invitation of the amici to base their decision on the concept of a minimum core obligation. In doing so the Court articulated a range of con- cerns relating to the concept. These included the assumed inflexibility of the minimum core, dif- ficulties in setting minimum standards in the context of varying needs and opportunities for accessing the rights, the lack of institutional competence for determining minimum standards, and the impossibility of giving everyone access to even a ‘core’ service immediately.71 However, the minimum core obligation, properly conceived, is neither an absolute duty nor a rigid stan- dard. Rather, it establishes a high threshold of justification when a deprivation of ‘essential’ lev- els of socio-economic goods and services is at issue. The State is required to show that it has exhausted all available methods, and that its resources are ‘demonstrably inadequate’72 to meeting those needs. This raises the central importance of justification in ensuring the strong protection of socio-economic rights. This issue will be revisited in Part V below. Human Dignity in Interpreting Socio-Economic Rights 155 67 Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC) para 36; Minister of Health v Treatment Action Campaign 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC) para 70. 68 In Khosa & Others v Minister of Social Development and Others; Mahlaule and Another v Minister of Social Development and Others 2004 (6) BCLR 569 (CC), the Court (per Mokgoro J) stated: ‘The right of access to social security, including social assistance, for those unable to support themselves and their depen- dants is entrenched because as a society we value human beings and want to ensure that people are afford- ed their basic needs. A society must seek to ensure that the basic necessities of life are accessible to all if it is to be a society in which human dignity, freedom and equality are foundational’: (at para 52) [emphasis added, footnotes omitted]. Nussbaum argues: ‘Programs aimed at raising general or average well-being do not improve the situation of the least well-off, unless they go to work directly to improve the quality of those people’s lives. If we combine this observation with the thought…that each person is valuable and wor- thy of respect as an end, we must conclude that we should look not just to the total or the average, but to the functioning of each and every person. We may call this the principle of each person as end’: Women and Human Development (note 3 above) at 56. 69 General Comment No. 3 (Fifth session, 1990) The Nature of States Parties Obligations (art 2(1) of the Covenant), UN doc E/1991/23 at para 10. 70 Ibid. 71 Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC) paras 29 – 33; Minister of Health v Treatment Action Campaign 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC) paras 26 – 39. 72 General Comment No 3 (note 69 above) para 11. 1 5 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E Thus far I have argued that the value of human dignity can enrich our socio-economic rights jurisprudence, first, by justifying claims against social resources when groups lack the material conditions necessary for the development of their capabilities as human beings. Second, respect and concern for the dignity of each person requires an approach that considers the impact of the deprivation upon the actual needs and circumstances of the individuals and groups con- cerned. Finally, it requires an appropriate response to these conditions. Urgent needs and severe deprivations demand a strong, immediate response. We give expression to the value of human dignity in our constitutional jurisprudence by placing the State under a stringent burden of jus- tification in claims involving a deprivation of basic needs. However, the use of human dignity in socio-economic rights jurisprudence is not without its pitfalls. As critics have cautioned in relation to South Africa’s equality jurisprudence,73 there is a danger that human dignity in our socio-economic jurisprudence will result in a focus on sub- jective personality issues such as the claimants’ feelings of self worth and self-respect. This focus can divert attention away from the real issue of the impact of the deprivation on claimants. The Canadian Supreme Court decision in Gosselin illustrates how differing conceptions of human dignity can influence the outcome of a social benefits claim.74 A class action was brought challenging social security regulations in Quebec which set the base amount of welfare benefits for adults between the ages of eighteen and thirty years at about one-third the base amount payable to those thirty years and over. This amounted to a difference between $170 per month compared to $466 per month (for the over 30 years and over age group). The latter was deemed by the legislature to constitute ‘the bare minimum for the sustainment of life.’75 The only way that those under 30 years could raise their benefits was to participate in various edu- cational and employability programmes. However, for the majority of young welfare recipients like the appellant participation in these programmes was fraught with difficulties, including their restrictive eligibility requirements and the limited number of places available.76 The Supreme Court of Canada had to consider whether the challenged regulation violated section 15 (equality right) of the Charter on the grounds that it discriminated on the basis of age. In addition, violations of section 7 of the Charter77 and section 45 of the Quebec Charter of Rights and Freedoms 78 were also alleged. The majority of the Court found no violations of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms or the Quebec Charter. In regard to section 15, the majority held that a reasonable person in the claimant’s circumstances would have perceived the government’s positive motives in creating an incentive-based welfare scheme for young people. According to the 73 See Part II above and the works cited there. 74 Gosselin v Quebec (Attorney General) 2002 SCC 84 221 DLR (4th). 75 Gosselin v Quebec (Attorney General) 2002 SCC 84 221 DLR (4th) at paras 251, 285 (per Bastarche J), and at para 334 (per Arbour J). 76 Thus the government of Quebec had only made 30 000 programme places available even though 85 000 single people under 30 years of age were on social assistance. See Gosselin v Quebec (Attorney General) 2002 SCC 84 221 DLR (4th) para 283. Four of the dissenting judgments on s 15 raised serious issues regarding the accessibility of these programmes and questioned whether the regulation was really designed to enhance the long-term situation of those under 30 years as opposed to simply saving money. See, for example, the discussion by Bastarche J at paras 276 – 283, and Arbour J at para 393. 77 Section 7 of the Charter provides that: ‘Everyone has the right to life, liberty and security of the person and the right not to be deprived thereof except in accordance with the principles of fundamental justice’. 78 Section 45 of the Quebec Charter provides that every person in need has a right to ‘measures of financial assistance and to social measures provided for by law, susceptible of ensuring such person an acceptable standard of living’. government this scheme was designed to promote the long-term employability of young peo- ple. Thus making welfare payments conditional in this manner did not violate the dignity or human worth of persons under 30 years of age.79 This can be contrasted with the more impacts-based approach to human dignity in the dissenting judgment of L’Heureux-Dubé J. After dealing with the practical effects of the regulation on the claimant’s ability to meet basic subsistence needs,80 she considered whether the claimant would perceive that her dignity had been threatened: …The reasonable claimant…would have been told that the long-term goal of the leg- islative scheme was to affirm her dignity. The reasonable claimant would also likely have been a member of the 88.8 percent who were eligible for the programs and whose income did not rise to the levels available to all adults 30 years of age and over…. The reasonable claimant would have made daily life choices in the face of an imminent and severe threat of poverty. The reasonable claimant would likely have suffered malnour- ishment. She might have turned to prostitution and crime to make ends meet. The rea- sonable claimant would have perceived that as a result of her deep poverty she had been excluded from full participation in Canadian society. She would have perceived that her right to dignity was infringed as a sole consequence of being under 30 years of age, a factor over which, at any given moment, she had no control…81 In L’Heureux-Dubé J’s judgment, the legislature’s good motives did not outweigh the severe impact of the regulation on the claimant’s physical and psychological integrity and her human dignity as a member of Canadian society. Her approach to the question whether there was a correspondence between the ground of distinction and the actual needs and circumstances of the affected group is also significant. In this regard, she held that ‘there should be a strong presumption that a legislative scheme which causes individuals to suffer severe threats to their physical and psychological integri- ty as a result of their possessing a characteristic which cannot be changed does not adequately take into account the needs, capacity or circumstances of the individual or group in question.’82 The approach of the majority in Gosselin to the assessment of whether human dignity had been infringed by the relevant regulation illustrates the dangers of a narrow, ‘personality inter- ests’-type approach to human dignity in assessing the constitutionality of a group’s exclusion from social benefits. This is further complicated by the introduction of an objective element, focusing not on the actual experiences of the applicant, but on conjecture regarding what a rea- sonable person in the applicant’s position would feel. As Sandy Fredman argues, ‘[t]he reason- able person turns out to be no more than the government’s own perception of its policy aims, Human Dignity in Interpreting Socio-Economic Rights 157 79 Gosselin v Quebec (Attorney General) 2002 SCC 84 221 DLR (4th) paras 52 – 53, 65 (per McLachlin CJC). In Law (note 59 above), the Supreme Court of Canada had held that the key issue in determining whether a distinction conflicts with sec 15(1) is whether ‘a reasonable person in circumstances similar to those of the claimant would find that the legislation which imposes differential treatment has the effect of demeaning his or her dignity’ having regard to the individual’s or group’s traits, history, and circumstances’: (para 60; cited in Gosselin v Quebec (Attorney General) 2002 SCC 84 221 DLR (4th) at para 25). 80 She found that the regulation in question exposed Ms Gosselin to the risk of severe poverty and in so doing breached her psychological and physical integrity. For example, she pointed out that in 1987, the monthly cost of proper nourishment was $152 whereas the guaranteed monthly welfare payment to young adults was $170: Gosselin v Quebec (Attorney General) 2002 SCC 84 221 DLR (4th) para 130. 81 Gosselin v Quebec (Attorney General) 2002 SCC 84 221 DLR (4th) paras 131 – 132. 82 Gosselin v Quebec (Attorney General) 2002 SCC 84 221 DLR (4th) para 135 [emphasis added]. 1 5 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E thus underscoring the deference of the standard of review.’83 The majority in Gosselin is too deferential to legislative choices that result in a vulnerable group suffering severe deprivation osten- sibly to promote the longer-term objectives of greater self-sufficiency and employability among youth on welfare. The minority judgments, in contrast, emphasise the impact on young welfare benefici- aries of the exclusion from a minimally adequate standard of benefits. The infringement of human dignity arises from the fact that the exclusion seriously undermines the physical and psychological integrity of young welfare beneficiaries. This places a burden on the State to justify the exclusion based on compelling evidence and arguments. The minority concludes that the consequences were of such a severe nature that they could not be justified by the state’s long-term objectives.84 The minority’s approach to human dignity in Gosselin holds the most potential for positive- ly influencing our socio-economic rights jurisprudence. The final section examines how the value of human dignity can influence our socio-economic rights jurisprudence to make it more responsive to claims for the provision of basic human needs. V Strengthening our Constitutional Response to Basic Needs Claims In many respects the evolving jurisprudence on socio-economic rights gives effect to the value of human dignity developed thus far. The Court endorses positive state measures to achieve access to socio-economic rights, a context-sensitive evaluation of reasonableness, and the requirement that a reasonable government programme includes short-term relief for those in urgent need and living in intolerable conditions. This applies even if the overall programme is statistically successful in the long-term in advancing people’s access to socio-economic rights.85 The Court’s model of review for positive socio-economic rights claims86 centres on the rea- 83 S Fredman ‘Providing Equality: Substantive Equality and the Positive Duty to Provide’ unpublished paper deliv- ered at SAJHR Conference, 5 – 7 July 2004 (on file with author), at 11. See also G Brodsky ‘Gosselin v Quebec (Attorney General): Autonomy with a Vengeance’ (2003) 15 Canadian Journal of Women and the Law 194. 84 Thus, for example, Arbour J held as follows in considering the sec 1 limitation inquiry (having found that the regulation breaches the s 7 rights to life and security of the person): ‘..it is difficult to accept that denial of the basic means of subsistence is rationally connected to values of promoting the long-term liberty and inherent dig- nity of young adults. Indeed, the long-term importance of continuing education and integration into the work- force is undermined where those at whom such “help” is directed cannot meet their basic short-term subsistence requirements. Without the ability to secure the immediate needs of the present, the future is little more than a far- off possibility, remote both in perception and in reality’: Gosselin v Quebec (Attorney General) 2002 SCC 84 221 DLR (4th) para 392. This also has resonance with the rationale in Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC). Here the government’s rational housing programme that was geared to the long-term goal of providing housing for all was nonetheless constitutionally defective for its failure to attend to short-term, urgent housing needs (see notes 64 - 66 above and accompanying text). 85 Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC) paras 44, 68 and see the Court’s order at para 99. 86 These claims involve two main situations. The first is the exclusion of a particular group from an existing social programme, the second entails the absence of a suitable programme providing access to particular benefits. In the first type of situation, as Khosa & Others v Minister of Social Development and Others; Mahlaule and Another v Minister of Social Development and Others 2004 (6) BCLR 569 (CC) illustrates, socio-economic rights and equality claims may often overlap. In the second situation, litigants may rely on the socio-economic rights provisions in the Bill of Rights to argue that the State is under a duty to adopt an appropriate programme ‘capable of facilitating the realisation of the right’ in question. See Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC) para 41. The absence of a programme catering for the provision of basic needs may also engage the right to equality interpreted substantively. sonableness inquiry. The fundamental question to be answered by the Court in such cases is whether the measures adopted by the State (or the failure to adopt appropriate measures) are reasonable in the circumstances. The reasonableness inquiry is further conditioned by the qualifying phrases in the second subsections of sections 26 and 27, namely the availability of resources and the latitude of ‘progressive realisation’ afforded the State.87 The Court is clear- ly reluctant to dictate particular policy choices to government. Instead it contemplates in Grootboom that ‘a wide range of possible measures’ would meet the requirements of rea- sonableness and thus comply with sections 26 and 27.88 It is certainly appropriate that the Court respects the primary role of the democratically elected legislature in relation to socio- economic policy. The executive also has particular institutional competency to design and implement appropriate policies and programmes. Reasonableness review provides the courts with a flexible, context-sensitive tool for adjudicating positive socio-economic rights claims.89 However, its application in relation to claims involving a deprivation of the basic necessities of life is inadequate. The stakes are high for the individuals and groups who approach the Court for relief, entailing severe threats to life, health and the ability to function in society. I have sought to develop the argument that a failure by society to respond in proportion to the seri- ousness of the deprivations faced by its members represents a failure to value their fundamen- tal dignity as human beings. In this section I will argue why I believe that the judicial protec- tion of these claims is insufficient, and how it could be improved. Stronger judicial potential of these claims will also signal to the State the constitutional importance of a robust response to situations of severe material deprivation. One of the shortcomings of the current structure of reasonableness review is that individual litigants bear an onerous burden of proof and persuasion to demonstrate the unreasonableness of government programmes. The Court has made it clear that sections 26 and 27 confer no direct entitlement to claim immediate delivery of goods and services from the State only a right to require government to adopt a reasonable programme.90 Thus it is not enough for a group of litigants to approach the Court alleging that they are poor and seriously malnourished, there- by establishing a prima facie violation of the right to food in section 27 of the Constitution. Instead litigants will have to show that the State’s actions or omissions are unreasonable in terms of the second subsection of section 27. To do so, they will have to review a wide range of government social programmes, and assess their reasonableness in the context of the State’s Human Dignity in Interpreting Socio-Economic Rights 159 87 Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC) paras 38, 41, 45-6. Although ‘progressive realisation’ affords the State the latitude of not requiring immediate realisation of the right, the Court also affirms that it imposes specific obligations on the State to make demonstrable progress in facilitating access to the rights, and in avoiding retrogressive measures: see Grootboom para 45. 88 Grootboom para 41. 89 The following key features of a reasonable government programme to realise socio-economic rights were developed by the Court in the Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC) and the Minister of Health v Treatment Action Campaign 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC) cases: the pro- gramme must be comprehensive, coherent, coordinated; it must be balanced and flexible, making appro- priate provision for short, medium and long-term needs, and not exclude a significant segment of society; it must include reasonable provision for those in urgent need; it must be reasonably conceived and imple- mented; it must be transparent, and its contents must be made known effectively to the public. See Grootboom paras 39 – 43; Treatment Action Campaign para 123. 90 Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC) paras 41, 95; Minister of Health v Treatment Action Campaign 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC) 32 – 39, and 125. 1 6 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E capacity and available resources.91 Establishing the unreasonableness of a disparate set of gov- ernment programmes in the light of the State’s available resources will be a matter of great fac- tual and legal complexity which will often be beyond the capacity of indigent and vulnerable groups.92 It thus does not facilitate the practical justiciability of this class of claims.93 In cases (such as the one discussed above) where people will face irreparable harm through not having their basic needs met, a more appropriate response would be to give the applicants the benefit of a presumption of unreasonableness. The effect would be that prima facie unrea- sonableness is established when a disadvantaged group shows that they lack access to the social goods and services that are required to sustain life, health and a basic level of functioning. The burden would shift to the State to rebut this presumption with compelling reasons. This pre- sumption would not be dissimilar to that operating in the context of the equality clause where discrimination on a listed ground is presumptively unfair.94 A clear presumption in favour of this category of socio-economic rights claimants recognises that a social failure to value human dignity is at stake when individuals and groups experience severe socio-economic deprivations. These groups are denied the opportunity to survive and to develop their capabilities. Respect and concern for the value and intrinsic worth of the individuals so afflicted should trigger a pre- sumption of unreasonableness and place a burden of justification on the State. It should be evident that this approach does not require the setting of inflexible minimum standards of delivery for each socio-economic right. As the Court observed in Grootboom, such an approach would be insensitive to the varying needs and circumstances of differently situat- ed groups in society.95 It also does not impose an absolute standard of performance on the State regardless of the social and economic context. It does require placing a strong burden of justi- fication on the State regarding the absence of basic levels of provisioning for groups living in poverty.96 91 The Court indicated that it would take into account the ‘interconnectedness’ of rights’ in assessing whether the state has fulfilled its obligations: Grootboom para 24. Among the measures that the Court indicated would be relevant in relation to access to housing were steps to make the rural areas of the country more viable so as to limit the migration of people from rural to urban areas in search of jobs (para 34). It also indicated that social assistance programmes put in place under sec 27 ‘would be relevant to the state’s obli- gations in respect of other socio-economic rights’: (para 36). 92 See in this regard the submissions of the amici in Treatment Action Campaign (Community Law Centre and IDASA) (24 April 2002, on-line at: www.communitylawcentre.org.za/ser/docs_2002/TAC_MTCT_Case_ Heads_of_Arguments.doc) at para 31.1. 93 The impact of the Court’s rejection of the concept of a minimum core obligation on the practical justicia- bility of socio-economic rights was developed by Adv Wim Trengove in representing the amici curiae in the Treatment Action Campaign case. They argued that practical justiciability is of particular importance in the enforcement of socio-economic rights because the purpose of these rights is to protect the interests of the poor who lack access to basic amenities of life: ‘For most of them, the right of access to court is already a paper right and not a practical reality. The very socio-economic rights designed for their protection and advancement must accordingly not be interpreted in a way that makes enforcement practically impossible’: (para 30.2). 94 Section 9(5). 95 See note 71 above and accompanying text. As Nussbaum argues, ‘individuals vary greatly in their needs for resources and in their abilities to convert resources into valuable functionings’: Women and Human Development (note 3 above) at 68. She gives the examples of a pregnant or lactating woman who needs more nutrients than a nonpregnant woman, a child needs more protein than an adult and a person with paralysed limbs needs many more resources to achieve the same level of mobility as a person without this disability. See further the discussion at 68 – 70. 96 See the similar presumption suggested by L’Heureux-Dubé J in Gosselin v Quebec (Attorney General) 2002 SCC 84 221 DLR (4th): see note 82 above and accompanying text. However, given the nature of the deprivations at stake and the seriousness of the consequences for the affected groups, this should not be an easy burden to discharge. A rigorous standard of scrutiny is required. In terms of the relational concept of human dignity I have sought to devel- op, dignity fails to be protected when the standard of justification demanded of government in respect of a failure to fulfil basic needs is low. A response that is not proportionate to the nature of the deprivation and its impact communicates a message that the affected group is not wor- thy of equal respect and concern.97 I suggest two elements of a stricter review standard for this category of claims. A stricter standard of scrutiny would require a compelling government purpose for failure to ensure that vulnerable groups have access to basic needs. Competing state priorities and resources-based justifications often give the Courts the most difficulty as they raise issues of separation of powers and institutional competence.98 However, respect for the dignity of human beings requires a serious engagement with these justifications. It is not sufficient as the Court did in TAC to simply assert that ‘[i]t is impossible to give everyone access even to a “core” service immediately.’99 The State should at least be required to establish the factual underpinnings of its justifications based on resources.100 There are different formulations of the threshold to be met concerning resource-based justifications for limiting access to constitution- al rights. For example, the UN Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights requires States to show that their resources are ‘demonstrably inadequate’ for meeting basic needs in the context of other equally important government purposes.101 In Eldridge v British Columbia Human Dignity in Interpreting Socio-Economic Rights 161 97 In Khosa & Others v Minister of Social Development and Others; Mahlaule and Another v Minister of Social Development and Others 2004 (6) BCLR 569 (CC), the Court held that ‘when the rights to life, dignity and equality are implicated in cases involving socio-economic rights, they have to be taken into account along with the availability of human and financial resources in determining whether the state has complied with the con- stitutional standard of reasonableness’: (at para 44). Although not explicitly stated, this suggests a tightening of the review standard in a socio-economic rights case when life, dignity and equality are at stake. In Jaftha v Schoeman and others; Van Rooyen v Stoltz and Others 2005 (1) BCLR 78 (CC), the Court held that the rele- vant provisions of the Magistrates’ Court Act 32 of 1944 (permitting sales of execution against people’s homes for debt without judicial oversight) rendered people vulnerable to homelessness as they would no longer quali- fy for housing subsidies. Without such assistance ‘they may be rendered homeless and never able to restore the conditions for human dignity’: (para 39). The Court accordingly held, in the limitations analysis (s 36), that this constituted ‘a severe limitation of an important right’: (para 39). The European Court of Human Rights recent- ly held in Connors v The United Kingdom 2005 (40) EHRR 189 (judgment of 27 May 2004) that the eviction of a gypsy family from a council-owned cite constituted a serious interference with their right to respect for their ‘private and family life’ and their home in terms of article 8 of the European Convention of Human Rights (1950). The Court observed that article 8 ‘concerns rights of central importance to the individual’s identity, self- determination, physical and moral integrity, maintenance of relationships with others and a settled and secure place in the community’: (para 82). The consequence of the eviction was homelessness for the family ‘with the adverse consequences on security and well-being which that entails’: (para 85). These serious consequences war- ranted, in the Court’s opinion, ‘particularly weighty reasons of public interest by way of justification’: In these circumstances, ‘the margin of appreciation to be afforded to the national authorities must be regarded as corre- spondingly narrowed’: (para 86). 98 See, for example, Minister of Health v Treatment Action Campaign 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC): ‘It should be borne in mind that in dealing with such matters the courts are not institutionally equipped to make the wide-ranging factual and political enquiries necessary for determining what the minimum-core stan- dards…should be, nor for deciding how public revenues should most effectively be spent’: (para 37). 99 Minister of Health v Treatment Action Campaign 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC) para 35. 100 In the context of the positive duties imposed by civil and political rights such as the right to vote, the courts have required that the factual basis for justifications based on logistics and costs be established by the State in the context of a limitations enquiry: Minister of Home Affairs v National Institute for Crime Prevention (NICRO) & Others 2004 (5) BCLR 445 (CC) at paras 47 – 51. 101 See notes 69 and 70 above and accompanying text. 1 6 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E (Attorney General),102 the Canadian Supreme Court held that section 15(1) (equality) imposed positive duties on the government to ensure ‘reasonable accommodation’ of disadvantaged groups in government programmes to the point of ‘undue hardship.’103 Whatever formulation is adopted, the Court should scrutinise the State’s evidence and argu- ments closely with a view to assessing whether it constitutes a compelling justification in the context of current South African society for failing to provide basic needs. The State is not nec- essarily required to show the diversion of all resources to the provision of basic needs. Ideally basic needs claims should be addressed in the context of integrated social programmes as opposed to ad hoc, crisis interventions.104 Sometimes, however, temporary solutions may be essential to respond to individual needs until the groups can be catered for within mainstream programmes. What should be required is evidence that the State is taking concrete and well-tar- geted budgetary and other measures to effectively address the situation of those who are expe- riencing severe deprivations of basic needs. Despite the above statement in the TAC case, the Court in fact proceeded to carefully analyse the State’s resource-based justifications for the fail- ure to extend the provision of Nevirapine throughout the public health sector, and concluded that they were unconvincing.105 The Court’s decision in Khosa also illustrates that the Court is both willing and able to engage vigorously with the State’s resource-based justifications for fail- ing to fulfil socio-economic rights.106 The second element of a strengthened review standard concerns the inclusion of a more rigor- ous proportionality analysis.107 The Court comes close to a proportionality test by establishing, as an important factor in the reasonableness enquiry, whether the State has made provision for those in immediate need. As Danie Brand argues, the Court ‘leans significantly closer [to a proportional- ity test] by incorporating such an element into its standard of scrutiny, narrowing the range of pol- icy options that it would be legitimate for government to choose from and thinking about the rel- ative efficiency of different policy options.’108 In TAC, the Court required government to adopt a 102 (1997) 151 DLR (4th) 577 (SC). The Court was faced with a challenge to the failure of the Medical Services Commission of British Columbia to provide sign language interpretation for deaf patients in the health sys- tem. It held that this omission constituted a prima facie violation of their right to equal benefit of the law without discrimination under s 15(1) of the Charter. 103 Eldridge v British Columbia (Attorney General) (1997) 151 DLR (4th) 577 (SC) paras 77 – 80. In response to the government’s argument in the sec 1 (limitations) analysis that the appellants’ claim would have ‘a rip- ple effect throughout the health care field, forcing governments to spend precious health care dollars accom- modating the needs of a myriad of disadvantaged persons’ (at para 91), the Court held as follows: ‘The respondents have presented no evidence that this type of accommodation, if extended to other government services, will unduly strain the fiscal resources of the state. To deny the appellants’ claim on such conjec- tural grounds, in my view, would denude s 15(1) of its egalitarian promise and render the disabled’s goal of a barrier-free society distressingly remote’: (at para 92). 104 As the Court observed in Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC) a reasonable programme ‘must be balanced and flexible and make appropriate provision for attention to housing crises and to short, medium and long term needs’: (at para 43). 105 See notes 48 - 52 above and accompanying text. 106 Khosa & Others v Minister of Social Development and Others; Mahlaule and Another v Minister of Social Development and Others 2004 (6) BCLR 569 (CC) at paras 60 – 62 (the inclusion of permanent residents in the social grants system ‘will be only a small proportion of the total cost’). 107 Theunis Roux observes that, although the reasonableness test ‘undoubtedly requires the court to substitute its view of what the constitution requires – the inclusion of the excluded group – for that of the political branch- es’, it ‘stops short…of a full blown proportionality test’: T Roux ‘Legitimating Transformation: Political Resource Allocation in the South African Constitutional Court’ (2003) 10 Democratization 92 at 97. 108 D Brand ‘The Proceduralisation of South African Socio-Economic Rights Jurisprudence, or “What are Socio-Economic Rights For?” ’ in H Botha, A van der Walt and J van der Walt (eds) Rights and Democracy in a Transformative Constitution (2004) 33 at 41. particular policy, namely the provision of Nevirapine (or any other equally appropriate or better method) throughout the public health sector for the prevention of mother-to-child transmission of HIV. This was unavoidable given the fact that there was in fact very little scope for a range of pol- icy choices. Without the provision of Nevirapine (or a similar anti-retroviral drug), large numbers of infants would continue to be infected with HIV and die prematurely as a result of mother-to- child transmission. Where the State does have a legitimate range of policy choices to respond to basic needs claims it would be appropriate for the Court to give the legislature and executive the first opportunity to design an appropriate programme. However, this could be achieved at the remedial stage and should not preclude a finding that government has failed to fulfil its positive duties.109 The inclusion of a more explicit proportionality analysis should include a requirement that gov- ernment show that there are not less restrictive means to achieve its purposes than a total denial of access to basic socio-economic goods and services.110 This should also entail showing that it has taken steps to mitigate the harms suffered as a result of the deprivation. Mitigating measures are particu- larly important when the provision of even a basic level of services to all who need them is unattain- able in the short term. The situation of these groups must remain a matter of high priority and pro- grammes aimed at alleviating the worst impact of the deprivations experienced must be put in place.111 In addition, the State must show that it is monitoring the deprivation of basic needs, and devising programmes and strategies for remedying the situation with the shortest possible period of time.112 In many respects, this inquiry resembles the limitations inquiry under section 36. This is an inevitable consequence of the model of reasonableness review adopted by the Court for meas- uring compliance with the State’s positive obligations under sections 26 and 27. In the Khosa case, the Court alluded to the ‘difficulty in applying section 36 of the Constitution to the socio- economic rights entrenched in sections 26 and 27 of the Constitution.’113 The Court held that Human Dignity in Interpreting Socio-Economic Rights 163 109 This could be facilitated through the use of the remedy of supervisory jurisdiction, which is discussed fur- ther below. 110 J De Waal, I Currie and MG Erasmus describe this element of the proportionality analysis as follows: ‘The limi- tation will not be proportionate if other means could be employed to achieve the same ends that will either not restrict rights at all, or will not restrict them to the same extent. The Bill of Rights Handbook (4th ed) (2001) 161 – 162. In Eldridge v British Columbia (Attorney General) (1997) 151 DLR (4th) 577 (SC), the Canadian Supreme Court held, in its sec 1 (limitations) enquiry, that the government had ‘manifestly failed to demonstrate that it has a reasonable basis for concluding that a total denial of medical interpretation services for the deaf con- stituted a minimum impairment of their rights’: (para 87). The Ministry of Health had decided not to fund the interpretation programme even in part. In this regard, the Court held: ‘Other options such as the partial or inter- im funding of the program offered by the Western Institute for the Deaf and Hard of Hearing, or the institution of a scheme requiring users to pay either a portion of the cost of interpreters or the full amount if they could afford to do so, were either not considered or were considered and rejected’: (at para 93). 111 In General Comment No 3 (note 69 above), the UN Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights empha- sised that ‘even where the available resources are demonstrably inadequate, the obligation remains for a State party to strive to ensure the widest possible enjoyment of the relevant rights under the prevailing circumstances’: (at para 11). It goes on to highlight the continuing obligation to protect the poor even during periods of resource scarcity: ‘Similarly, the Committee underlines the fact that even in times of severe resource constraints whether caused by a process of adjustment, of economic recession, or by other factors the vulnerable members of society can and indeed must be protected by the adoption of relatively low-cost targeted programmes’: (para 12). 112 The UN Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights has adopted the view that the State’s duties ‘to monitor the extent of realization, or more especially of the non-realization, of economic, social and cul- tural rights and to devise strategies and programmes for their promotion, are not in any way eliminated as a result of resource constraints’: General Comment No 3 (note 69 above), para 11. 113 Khosa & Others v Minister of Social Development and Others; Mahlaule and Another v Minister of Social Development and Others 2004 (6) BCLR 569 (CC) para 83. See also the academic commentaries cited by the Court at note 88 of the judgment. 1 6 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E it was not necessary to decide the issue of whether ‘a different threshold of reasonableness’ is called for in sections 26 and 27 than is the case in section 36.114 An advantage of conducting the inquiry into the justifiability of the State’s acts or omission in terms of the general limita- tions clause (section 36) is the requirement of a law of general application. This has the impor- tant benefit that limitations on people’s access to basic needs would have to be publicly debat- ed and adopted by the elected representatives of the people.115 However, if the internal limita- tions in sections 26(2) and 27(2) are going to do the major work in assessing the State’s com- pliance with its positive duties, it should encompass a high standard of justification, including a more rigorous proportionality analysis, at least in respect of basic needs claims. The standard of scrutiny may vary in intensity, depending on the nature of the interests at stake. A strict level of judicial scrutiny is appropriate when a case concerns the claimants’ inability to gain access to a minimally adequate level of resources to survive and function effectively.116 This strict form of scrutiny should not be triggered only in emergency or crisis situations. The Court in Grootboom also referred in its order to those ‘living in intolerable conditions’.117 This clearly con- templates a broader set of circumstances than emergencies. In insisting on the strong judicial pro- tection of basic survival needs, we should not lose sight of the fact that we are concerned not only with physical survival, but the essential material conditions that each person needs to develop their capabilities and to function effectively as members of society. This includes the physical, psycho- logical and social dimensions of their personhood.118 The standard of review can be progressively relaxed when claims are made to levels of social provisioning that are less closely related to peo- ple’s ability to survive and function effectively in society. This graduated standard of review is accommodated by the concept of ‘progressive realisation’ in sections 26(2) and 27(2).119 Thus while a stronger standard of review is justified for basic needs claims, it seems appropriate to allow the State a greater latitude (in terms of both time and resource allocation priorities) when the claim involves more tertiary levels of provisioning. In the case of children, material deprivation can have a profound impact on the future development of their basic capabilities, calling for heightened scrutiny of the impact of such deprivations.120 114 Khosa & Others v Minister of Social Development and Others; Mahlaule and Another v Minister of Social Development and Others 2004 (6) BCLR 569 (CC) para 84. For a recent view on the relationship between the internal limitations in sections 26 and 26 and the general limitations clause in s 36, see K Iles ‘Limiting Socio-Economic Rights: Beyond the Internal Limitations Clauses’ (2004) 20 SAJHR 448. 115 It is noteworthy that in respect of the negative violation of the duty not to deprive people of existing access to socio-economic rights, the Court has now held in Jaftha v Schoeman and Others; Van Rooyen v Stoltz and Others 2005 (1) BCLR 78 (CC) that justification is appropriately considered in terms of the general limitations clause. See paras 31 to 34. 116 David Bilchitz refers to people’s basic or ‘urgent’ interest ‘in being free from threats to one’s survival, being free from severe physical suffering, and not being exposed to serious health risks that impair one’s ability to act’: ‘Giving Socio-Economic Rights Teeth: The Minimum Core and its Importance’ (2002) 118 SALJ 484 at 490. He argues that the urgency of the interests at stake justifies strong judicial protection (at 491). 117 Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC) para 99. 118 See the discussion of Nussbaum’s list of ‘central human capabilities’ at notes 26 to 29 and accompanying text. Bilchitz also refers to people’s more extensive interest ‘in living in an environment that is conducive to their flourishing and development on physical, emotional and mental levels’: (note 116 above) 490. 119 See the discussion of the Court’s interpretation of ‘progressive realisation’ in Liebenberg (note 12 above) ch 33, 41 – 42. 120 The drafting of section 28(1)(c) of the Constitution suggests a stronger standard of scrutiny for children’s socio-economic rights. Prima facie children are guaranteed a basic level of socio-economic rights, with lim- itations to this entitlement falling to be determined in terms of the general limitations clause (sec 36). For a critical evaluation of the Court’s approach to the interpretation of children’s socio-economic rights, see Liebenberg (note 12 above) ch 33, 48 – 52. The final area where the Court could strengthen its constitutional response to socio-economic rights claims is in the area of remedial jurisprudence. A detailed discussion of this aspect is beyond the scope of the present paper. However, it is evident that the nature of the urgent inter- ests at stake in the socio-economic rights claims that are the focus of this paper demands an appropriate and effective remedy. The orders handed down in cases such as TAC will ultimate- ly result in the extension of critical benefits to significant numbers of people.121 However, the Court has indicated that a finding that a government programme is unreasonable will not nec- essarily imply that all in desperate need should receive relief immediately.122 Nonetheless, as the Court indicated in TAC, ‘[e]very effort must, however, be made to do so as soon as rea- sonably possible.’123 There will be situations where it would be impossible to immediately rem- edy a situation that has been found to be in violation of sections 26 and 27, or where the grant- ing of relief to only the litigants before the court would be inequitable to other similarly-situ- ated groups. The Court’s broad power to make ‘any order that is just and equitable’124 pro- vides the remedial flexibility to make appropriate orders in these situations. However, sight should never be lost of the fact that there are serious interests of human survival and dignity at stake. The language of the orders handed down by the Court should reflect this fact, and sig- nal the requirement that the State remedy the defect ‘diligently and without delay.’125 This is exemplified in the mandatory nature of the order handed down in TAC combined with the duty to take the steps specified in the order ‘without delay.’126 When it is not manifestly inappro- priate or unjust, the Court should lean in favour of granting individual remedies to the suc- cessful litigants.127 This reflects the value we should place on the dignity of each person. The TAC order has been criticised for its failure to grant the supervisory order sought by the applicants.128 While the Court accepted that such orders could be given in appropriate cir- cumstances, it indicated that that they should generally not be made in those terms ‘unless this is necessary’ to secure compliance with a court order.129 The Court went on to express its faith that the government would respect and execute its orders. However, an equally important con- Human Dignity in Interpreting Socio-Economic Rights 165 121 This of course assumes that the State diligently executes the Court’s orders and that there is effective mon- itoring and advocacy in respect of the implementation of the orders by institutions such as the SA Human Rights Commission, the press and NGOs. On the efforts of the Treatment Action Campaign in seeking to ensure the implementation of the Treatment Action Campaign order, see M Heywood ‘Contempt or Compliance: The TAC Case after the Constitutional Court Judgment’ (2003) 4 ESR Review 7. 122 Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC) para 69; Minister of Health v Treatment Action Campaign 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC) para 125. 123 Treatment Action Campaign para 125. 124 Sec 172(1)(b) of the Constitution. 125 See sec 237 of the Constitution. 126 Treatment Action Campaign para 135. The Grootboom order has been criticised for its purely declaratory nature and the impact this had on the slow implementation of the order: see K Pillay ‘Implementation of Grootboom: Implications for the Enforcement of Socio-economic Rights’ (2002) 6 Law, Democracy & Development 255. 127 As the Court pointed out in August v Electoral Commission 1999 (3) SA 1 (CC): ‘We cannot deny strong actual claims timeously asserted by determinate people because of the possible existence of hypothetical claims that might conceivably have been brought by indeterminate groups’: (at para 30). 128 See D Bilchitz ‘Towards a Reasonable Approach to the Minimum Core: Laying the Foundations for Future Socio-economic Rights Jurisprudence’ (2003) 19 SAJHR 1 at 23 – 26. The High Courts in both the Grootboom and TAC cases handed down supervisory orders: Grootboom v Oostenberg Municipality & Others 2000 (3) BCLR 277 (C) at 293 H – 294 C; Treatment Action Campaign & Others v Minister of Health & Others 2002 (4) BCLR 356 (T) at 386 I – 384 H. 129 Minister of Health v Treatment Action Campaign 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC) para 129. 1 6 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E sideration, as Geoff Budlender has suggested, ‘is the risk of severe consequences (such as the loss of life)’ in the event of a failure by the government to comply with its obligations.130 In cases where severe economic deprivation threatens people’s lives and capacity for future devel- opment, this fact should weigh heavily with the Court in considering a supervisory order. This is particularly the case where the breach cannot be remedied by a single action,131 but requires a series of structural reforms and administrative actions taken over a period of time.132 Finally, if there are a range of policy options for responding to basic needs claims (as in the Grootboom situation), the remedy of supervisory jurisdiction can be formulated to allow the State to select the appropriate policy while retaining judicial supervision in respect of constitutionality of the policy choice and its implementation. In this way, a supervisory remedy may be crafted that respects the roles and competencies of the legislature and executive without abdicating judicial responsibility for the enforcement of socio-economic rights. VI Conclusion At the core of the value of human dignity lies the injunction to respect the intrinsic worth of all human beings. Drawing on Nussbaum’s work, I have argued that we value human beings by viewing them in the context of the reality of their lives and inquiring what they are actually able to be and do. Through this inquiry we are confronted with the importance of social power rela- tions and material conditions for people’s ability to survive and develop their capabilities as individual and social beings. To constitute ourselves as a society that values human dignity, we must develop appropriate responses to conditions of disadvantage and material deprivation in social policy and constitu- tional adjudication. In constitutional adjudication this requires a focus on the actual impact of the State’s actions or omissions on the life chances of disadvantaged groups. It also demands a proportionately urgent response to conditions that undermine people’s ability to survive and develop their capabilities. This is promoted by placing a strong burden of justification on the State in claims where a deprivation of access to basic human needs is at stake. This approach does not advocate a two-tier standard of review based on a rigid distinction between ‘core’ and ‘non-core’ needs. If minimum core obligations are conceived as universal, abstract and a-contextual standards of state provision, they will certainly be unjust to a range of groups who do not fit the background norms and conditions that inform the setting of these standards. Instead what is envisaged is a continuum of judicial scrutiny informed by a contex- tual, evolving assessment of the position of the claimant in society, the nature of the resource or service to which access is sought, and the impact of the denial of such access on the affect- ed group. In many respects the Constitutional Court’s evolving jurisprudence on socio-economic rights 130 G Budlender ‘Access to Courts’ (2004) 121 SALJ 339 at 358. 131 For example, the ‘reading in’ remedy granted in Khosa & Others v Minister of Social Development and Others; Mahlaule and Another v Minister of Social Development and Others 2004 (6) BCLR 569 (CC) to cure the omission of permanent residents from the Social Assistance Act 59 of 1992 (at para 98). 132 See: W Trengove ‘Judicial Remedies for Violations of Socio-Economic Rights’ (1999) 1 ESR Rev 8 8 at 9 – 10. promotes the contextual, relational conception of human dignity developed in this paper. However, our constitutional response to claims of material deprivation could be strengthened, and I have suggested how this could be accomplished within the Court’s model of reasonable- ness review and remedial jurisprudence. A society characterised by stark inequalities and deep poverty is most in peril of failing to value the human dignity of the poor. The role of the Constitutional Court is to hold us account- able to the vision we articulated when we adopted our Constitution ‘so as to -…[i]mprove the quality of life of all citizens and free the potential of each person.’133 Human Dignity in Interpreting Socio-Economic Rights 167 133 Preamble to the 1996 Constitution. The Fiscal Implications of Social and Economic Justice: An Overview of the Changing Theoretical Framework E L S A B É L O O T S Professor, Department of Economics, University of the Free State, Bloemfontein I Introduction The addition of economic and social rights, or second-generation rights as they are sometimes classified, has vastly expanded the claimed domain of human rights. Economic, social and cul- tural rights1 are no longer neglected as they once were, relative to civil and political rights. Despite this improved awareness, we still live in a world where social and economic justice is frequently ignored and repeatedly violated and threatened. In many quarters threats are caused and entrenched by the process of globalisation, global environmental destruction and political instability between and within countries. In contrast with these external threats, a large num- ber of developing countries that are sensitive to calls for social and economic justice simply do not have the fiscal means to address all of these needs or injustices. The development of awareness of social and economic rights issues within the international community took quite some time. While the General Assembly of the United Nations adopted the Universal Declaration of Human Rights on 10 December 1948 it was not immediately fol- lowed by, in Smith’s2 words, ‘a binding enforceable tabulation of rights’. It took 18 years before consensus was reached on the text of the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1966) and a further ten years before the instrument attracted sufficient ratifi- cation to enter into force in 1976. The importance of social and economic rights was further strengthened by the influential 1986 Principles on the Implementation of Economic, Social and Cultural Rights as well by the 1997 Maastricht Guidelines on Violations of Economic, Social and Cultural Rights.3 Despite the fact that these declarations and guidelines have achieved wide recognition internationally and status within the United Nations, the framework on the core elements of these rights, the setting of standards and the identification of minimum state obli- gations are still in the development stage and incomplete. 1 Economic, social and cultural rights are grouped together in the International Covenant of Economic, Social and Cultural Rights. For the purpose of this research only the social and economic dimensions will be included. 2 RKM Smith Textbook in International Human Rights (2003). 3 For more details on the development of these declarations and guidelines, see Smith (note 2 above), and D Brand & S Russell (eds) Exploring the Core Content of Socio-economic Rights: South African and International Perspectives (2002). The state obligations and the related fiscal implications within the social and economic justice context are controversial. Two related issues are of importance when it comes to what the state’s obligations are in this regard. The first issue refers to the debate on equity and efficien- cy. The second issue refers to the particular rights included in the country’s constitution. Within the social and economic justice debate issues such as equity and efficiency are firmly embedded. A reasonably efficient economy where perfect competition exists and markets are clearing on a continuous basis should in theory also ensure sustainable social justice. An equitable social dis- pensation could in theory also support an efficient economy. This implies that equity and effi- ciency should in theory be mutually reinforcing. In practice, countries and communities that experience social and economic injustices are struggling to sustain equity and efficiency, and mostly regard them as trade-offs. The second issue, namely which social and economic rights are included in a particular coun- try’s constitution, also impact on the state’s responsibility. Apart from the fact that the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights includes rights such as equal pay for equal work, trade union rights, child labour laws, a number of educational rights and academic, scientific and artistic freedom, the South African Constitution has gone further and has included the aforementioned rights as well as several rights not explicitly stated in the Covenant. These include rights such as access to water and to a clean and healthy environ- ment.4 The South African Constitution5 therefore entrenched the following social and eco- nomic rights: labour rights; the right to have access to land, housing, health care services, suf- ficient food and social security; children’s rights to basic nutrition, shelter, basic health care and social services; the right to basic education and in some cases further education; and a number of detained person’s rights. These expanded and detailed lists of rights have serious implications for the state’s obligations in this regard. The dilemma of states having limited resources led to the development of the concept of min- imum state obligation. Two important questions arise from this minimum state obligation con- cept. The first question is how human rights in general and social and economic rights in par- ticular could be addressed if states do not have the available resources even to meet the mini- mum state obligation. The second question relates to the identification of a minimum state obli- gation if all the components of the stated rights are important and the ultimate goal is full implementation. The aim of this chapter is to discuss the latest approaches that have developed in theory and literature on social and economic justice on how to deal with these dilemmas. The analysis on this topic will commence with some historical background by discussing the way approaches and theories on social and economic justice were aligned with the political ide- ologies of the day. Each of these approaches will be linked to the role of the state, the main- stream theoretical economic thinking of the time and the implied fiscal implications. This will be followed by a discussion of the latest theoretical approaches to addressing social and eco- nomic justice, with particular reference to the changing structural and responsibility frame- works, respectively. In this regard the discussion will predominantly focus on the theoretical contribution of Amartya Sen and his role in the paradigm shift on development and human rights as reflected in the various Human Development Reports of the United Nations Development Programme. The analysis reveals that social and economic rights have increased in importance since the Fiscal Implications of Social and Economic Justice 169 4 Brand & Russell (note 3 above) at 13, 14. 5 Act 108 of 1996. 1 7 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E early 1990s. This trend, as well as the inclusion of third-generation rights, has blurred the pre- vious artificial division between first-, second- and third-generation rights to form a broader concern with all rights. The broader and extended redefinition of the concepts of development led to a convergence of the human rights agenda and the human development agenda, in both concept and action, including the notion that they are mutually reinforcing. This convergence has extended the leftist state-centred model of accountability to a more centre-leftist approach where the state’s responsibility changed to include non-state actors. Another important trend is the increased importance of the state’s obligation beyond national borders. II The Changing Framework of Human Rights: An Overview The starting point of this discussion is the notion that the appropriate distribution of income and wealth has been determined by the political system or ideology of the day. The economic system is normally aligned with this ideology in order to achieve maximum efficiency in the production and distribution of commodities. These particular ideologies formed the basis of the human rights debate over the past fifty years. From this basic starting point, the discussion will centre on the ideologies on the extreme right and left of the spectrum, as well as the more recent centre leftist approach, as illustrated in Figure 1. The framework in Figure 1 also refers to the role of the state within the particular ideology, the most prominent economic and/or social the- orists of the time and the implied state obligation. The extreme right of the spectrum is the free market ideologies such as the classic liberals and the neo-liberals. Classical liberalism entails economic liberalism (laissez-faire capitalism) and the belief that the market is a self-regulating mechanism that will deliver general prosperity and opportunities for all – in other words, will ensure social justice. The central pillars of neo-lib- eralism are the market and the individual. The neo-liberal goal is to ‘roll back the frontiers of Social democracy Modern liberalism Social democratic Rawls Large and continuous Sen Medium and declining Third way Competitive Rome and Lucas Classical liberalism Neo-liberalism MinimalDevelopmental Medium and continuous Friedman Von Hayek Minimal Ideologies Role of the state Theorists Fiscal implications Figure 1 FRAMEWORK FOR THE FISCAL IMPLICATIONS OF SOCIAL AND ECONOMIC RIGHTS the state’.6 Unregulated markets will deliver efficiency, growth and prosperity. These free mar- ket ideologies emphasised that the dead hand of the state has a damaging effect upon human affairs. These extreme right ideologies prefer a minimal state or in some case a developmental state where individuals enjoy the widest possible degree of freedom. State intervention in the economy is limited to the provision of a police force and military of some kind, as well as a judicial system. Economic, social, cultural, moral and other rights and responsibilities belong to the individual and are seen as the responsibility of civil society.7 Civil rights therefore pre- dominate over human rights. The leading economists within this paradigm are free-market economists such as Milton Friedman and Friedrich von Hayek, who viewed state intervention as something that reduces competition, efficiency and production. Due to the minimalist state and the lack of attention to human rights, state obligation is minimal and limited. Stronger emphasis on the need for social and economic justice originated predominantly within the social democracy and modern liberal paradigms, fitting into the extreme left of the spectrum. The ideology of social democracy represents a balance between the market and the state, between the individual and community. It is also in favour of a compromise between the capitalistic generation of wealth and a desire to distribute wealth in accordance with moral principles.8 The main characteristic of modern social democratic thought is a concern for the underdog in society – the weak and the vulnerable.9 Principles such as welfarism, redistribution and social justice are important. Social democracy overlaps with modern liberalism, which is more in favour of a large or interventionist government, implying economic management and social regulation. The most influential modern attempt to reconcile the principles of modern liberalism and social democracy with the politics of welfare and redistribution was undertaken by John Rawls in his Theory of Justice (1970). Rawls proposed a theory of justice as fairness that is based on the belief that social inequality can be justified only if it is of benefit to the least advantaged. It should pro- vide them with an incentive to work. For most people the fear of being poor will outweigh the desire to be rich; therefore redistribution and welfare can be defended on the grounds of fairness. The presumptions of his earlier work were modified in Political Liberalism (1993). Social-democratic states represent a shift from the negative minimalist view of the state to a positive view of the state. Social-democratic states intervene to bring about broader social restructuring, usually in accordance with principles of fairness, equality and social justice. They focus on creating an enabling state, dedicated to the principle of individual empowerment. From a fiscal viewpoint, this paradigm could contribute to a free for all principle or cradle to grave welfare, and the subsequent emergence of the so-called welfare state. The continued growth in public spending, with eroding economic incentives and personal freedom, constitutes a serious fiscal threat to economies since it is leading to government overload.10 Analysis in developed economies by Lindbeck, as well as by Tanzi and Schuknecht,11 argued that the wel- fare state has developed into a transfer state, where redistributions of income occur among peo- Fiscal Implications of Social and Economic Justice 171 6 A Heywood Politics (2002) at 96. 7 Heywood (note 6 above) at 95. 8 The European Social Charter of 1961, where jurisdiction was limited to Europe, gave rise to the leftist approach to the realisation of economic and social justice and the subsequent welfare-doctrine. 9 Heywood (note 6 above) at 57. 10 E Calitz & K Siebritz: ‘Macroeconomic Stability and Developmental Expectations: Fiscal Consolidation in Post-apartheid South Africa’ (2003) Paper Presented at the Biennial Conference of the Economic Society of South Africa, Somerset West: September 2003. 11 See reference in Calitz and Siebritz (note 10 above). 1 7 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E ple of comparable living standards, rather than from the rich to the poor. When expanding social expenditure coincides with recession and declining tax revenues, it could have serious fis- cal implications. This extreme leftist approach implies a large and continuous state obligation, with serious consequences for states with limited fiscal means. The analysis of the framework on social and economic justice shows that both the extreme right and leftist approaches failed in setting acceptable standards and responsibilities in ensur- ing social and economic justice for all. The extreme right approach envisaged minimum state intervention and required the individual through civil society to be responsible if social and eco- nomic rights are claimed. In contrast, the extreme leftist approach placed the responsibility for the provision of a broad spectrum of social and economics rights solely in the hands of the state. The state’s fiscal responsibility within these two approaches also varies between extremes of large and continuous and minimal and limited responsabilities. These two extreme approaches do not provide acceptable solutions to the problem of developing a framework for social and economic rights or to how these rights could be addressed in countries with limited fiscal means. The more recent trend in facilitating economic and social justice is a shift to the right from social-democratic states (or in some cases being seen as centre-left) and is known as the third way (see Figure 1). Third-way politics draws on various ideological traditions such as modern liberalism, one-nation conservatism and modernised social democracy.12 It serves as an alter- native to old-style social democracy and neo-liberalism. Within this framework the importance of the phenomenon of globalisation and its contribution of the knowledge economy is accept- ed, as are individual skills and both business and labour flexibility. Government still has a vital economic and social role, but this role is more focused and concentrates on enhancing interna- tional competitiveness through education and skills development and strengthening civil socie- ty to contain the pressures generated by market capitalism. Third-way proponents call for a balance between rights and entrepreneurialism, on the one hand, and social duty and moral responsibility, on the other. In contrast with cradle to grave welfare, third-way politics is in favour of the essential modern liberal belief of helping people to help themselves. This supports a workfare state (in contrast with a welfare state) in which government support in terms of ben- efits or education is conditional upon individuals seeking work and becoming self-reliant. The key third-way values are opportunity, responsibility and community involvement. Two of the most influential schools of thought within the so-called third way are those that emphasise endogenous growth, which tend to be more centrist in nature, and those of Amartya Sen, which are more centre-left in nature. Although the focus of this analysis will be predomi- nantly on the centre-left approach in general and specifically those of Sen, it is worth noting the views of the endogenous growth theories. The endogenous growth models13 propose an active role for public policy in the promotion of economic development through direct and indirect investment in human capital formation. They also support the encouragement of foreign private investment in knowledge-intensive industries. Although these models fit into the general third-way political stream, they offer no suggestions on how human rights will be addressed. In contrast, Sen’s contribution, which will be discussed subsequently, falls within the broader third-way stream. This latest trend in the facilitation and promotion of human rights in general and eco- 12 See Heywood (note 6 above) at 58, 59 for a detailed discussion. 13 See PM Romer ‘The Origins of Endogenous Growth’ (1994) Journal of Economic Perspectives at 8 for a detailed discussion on endogenous growth. nomic and social justice in particular recognises that civil society can play a crucial role in enhanc- ing the traditional function fulfilled by government. The recognition of the role of non-state actors constitutes a revolutionary advancement in the discourse on human rights. Apart from the fact that it reduces fiscal pressures on the state, evidence shows that it contributes in general towards greater self-reliance and the creation of capabilities. The general well-being of society entails a par- ticular role for the state vis-à-vis an efficient and equitable market, and a healthy environment in a just economic and social context.14 The various theories on and approaches to the changing structure as well as the shared responsibility between the state and civil society on matters per- taining to social and economic justice are discussed below. III Modern Social and Economic Justice Theories and Approaches: Changes in Structure and Responsibilities The movement from the extreme left thinking on social and economic justice to a more centre- leftist approach, where the responsibility for human rights is shared, is a paradigm shift from the traditional viewpoint held on the general framework of these rights. This shift is evident in the structure of these rights as well as in the conventional notion that these rights are the sole responsibility of the state. The structure and therefore the concept of rights directly influences the state’s duty or programme of action and they are therefore mutually reinforcing. (A) CHANGING STRUCTURAL FRAMEWORK The structural human rights framework has changed significantly in recent times. The shift in para- digm can be ascribed to the broader and more inclusive concern with all rights, the influence of the human development approach on the thinking on human rights, and, lastly, the narrowing of the divide and convergence between the human rights agenda and the human development agenda. The first and perhaps least prominent influence on the changing human rights framework is evident in the shift from a narrow and dominant focus on civil and political rights to a broad- er concern with all rights, including second-generation rights such as social, economic and cul- tural rights, as well as third-generation rights such as the right to development and the right to a safe environment. Although second-generation rights have been part of the original human rights framework, they have increased in prominence over the past decade or more. Their prominence was further strengthened by action from within the international legal human rights movement itself, where so-called third-generation rights such as the explicit right to development and gender rights were included in the human rights framework of the United Nations (see the 1986 UN Declaration on the Rights to Development and the Vienna World Conference on Human Rights of 1993). The fact that an ever-increasing number of ratifying countries have to report to various United Nations committees on their respective performanc- es also serves to enhance awareness in this regard. The second shift involves the increased awareness since the early 1990s of the importance of human development in the development process of countries.15 Where the earlier views on Fiscal Implications of Social and Economic Justice 173 14 N Malan ‘Civil Society and the Right to have Access to Social Security in South Africa’ (2004) Unpublished Research Paper, RAU: Johannesburg. 15 See the various Human Development Reports of the United Nations Development Program (UNDP) from 1991 to 2004 for details on the developments in the human development debate. 1 7 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E development were purely focused on a narrow top-down approach, where an increase in per capita income was seen as the only prerequisite for development, the human development approach is broader and bottom-up in nature. Under the auspices of human development the notion is held that development only takes place through the process of enlarging people’s choices by expanding human functionings and capabilities. According to the United Nations Development Program16 the essential capabilities are for people to lead a long and healthy life, to be knowledgeable and to have access to the resources needed for a decent standard of living. These capabilities reflect the freedom to achieve functionings (valuable things a person can do or be), implying that human development is freedom. Human development is ‘development of the people, for the people and by the people.’ 17 However, the most pronounced change in the structural framework is evident in the link between human rights and human development. These two concepts followed parallel paths in the past, as can be seen in the fact that human development was dominated by economists, social scientists and policy-makers, while political activists, lawyers and philosophers dominat- ed the human rights debate. Over the past decade the two hitherto parallel paths have con- verged in both concept and action, implying that the divide between the human rights agenda and the human development agenda is narrowing. The 2000 Human Development Report18 links the mutually reinforcing nature of the two concepts as follows: ‘Human development thus contributes to building a long-run strategy for the realisation of rights’. Amartya Sen, who won the Nobel Prize in 1998,19 has offered the most significant theoret- ical contribution to the conceptualisation of the human development and human rights debates, respectively. Through his theoretical contribution, he also firmly entrenched the link between the two concepts. Sen was critical of welfarism and utilitarianism, on the one hand, and of the Rawlsian approach, on the other. As Sen put it: ‘Economic growth cannot be sensibly treated as an end in itself. Development has to be more concerned with enhancing the lives we lead and the freedoms we enjoy’.20 He sees human rights as an important element of human develop- ment in general and social and economic freedoms in particular. Freedoms, or capabilities as he calls them, require that a distinction be made between substantive opportunities and freedom of processes.21 His capability approach, which was subsequently incorporated in the human development paradigm, focuses on what he calls the capability to function. This capability to function is what really matters for the status of a poor or non-poor person. Capability, which is the opportunity aspect of freedom, is the opportunity to achieve valuable combinations of human functionings. He distinguishes between realised functionings (what a person is actually able to do) or on the set of alternatives she has, or real opportunities. Functioning is what a per- son does with the commodities of given characteristics he or she then comes to possess or con- trol. He defines capabilities as ‘the freedom that a person has in terms of the choice of func- tioning, given his personal features and his command over commodities’. Functioning reflects the various things a person may value doing or being. This may vary from elementary ones such as being adequately nourished and being free from disease to taking part in the life of the com- munity and having self-respect. 16 UNDP (note 15 above) at 17. 17 UNDP (note 15 above) at 17. 18 UNDP (note 15 above) at 2. 19 Development as Freedom (1999); Commodities and Capabilities (1985); On Economic Inequality (1997). 20 A Sen Development as Freedom (1999). 21 A Sen ‘Elements of a Theory of Human Rights’ (2004) 32 Philosophy & Public Affairs at 332. Sen’s capability approach acknowledges that two persons can have different substantial opportunities, even in circumstances where they have the same set of means or incomes. This approach therefore distinguishes between means or income, on the one hand, and actual oppor- tunities on the other. Freedom is therefore the opportunity to achieve combinations of func- tionings. Sen22 remarks that the general idea of freedom with its many distinct components seems particularly relevant to the theory of justice. His contributions to this debate led to wider recognition of the idea that ‘human rights links directly to the safeguarding and advance of human freedoms’.23 With his capability approach Sen established the foundation on which the human develop- ment approach was based, and his theoretical contributions on freedom contributed to the con- vergence between the human development and human rights concepts. The redefining of the concept of human rights to include a broader and more inclusive viewpoint on the importance of all rights as well as the importance of choices for all people within the human development framework not only established a permanent link between the two, but also shifted the state’s obligations in almost all respects. (B) CHANGING RESPONSIBILITY FRAMEWORK Since the early 1990s the extreme leftist approach and its related state-centred model of account- ability to social and economic justice has been criticised from various quarters. The criticism came from state actors themselves in response to fiscal constraints as well as from non-state actors who are of the opinion that within the human development framework the range of choices of people could only be enlarged if they form part of the decision-making process on choices that affect their daily lives. Suggestions are coming to the fore on extension of the accountability from states to non-state actors as well as the state’s obligation beyond national borders. Two important and interrelated issues arise from this new notion on the state’s obligation: first the minimum state obligation, which is linked to the realisation of rights; and second how the state can strengthen and support social and economic rights within this new framework. On the realisation of rights, Sen provides answers firstly through his so-called threshold con- ditions, and secondly, through his so-called institutionalisation critique and feasibility cri- tique.24 In his reference to threshold conditions, he asks the question whether a specific human right is important enough to cross the threshold to social significance. His analysis of thresh- olds relates to both the seriousness and the social influenceability of particular freedoms or capabilities. On the institutional critique of economic and social rights, the importance of insti- tutions in the realisation of these rights is acknowledged, but when this does not exist, the eth- ical significance of these rights provides good grounds for seeking realisation through institu- tional expansion and reform. The feasibility critique argues that even with the best of efforts it may not be feasible to arrange the realisation of many of the alleged economic and social rights for all. Sen also asks why complete feasibility should be a condition of cogency of human rights when the objective is to work towards enhancing their actual realisation, if necessary through expanding their feasibility. An understanding must prevail that a change in the prevailing cir- cumstances must be striven for in order to make the unrealised rights realisable. Sen25 con- Fiscal Implications of Social and Economic Justice 175 22 Sen (note 21 above) at 335. 23 UNDP (note 15 above) at 15. 24 Sen (note 21 above) at 330, 346-348. 25 Sen (note 21 above) at 356. 1 7 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E cludes by referring to the fact that human rights are only sustainable by a continuous process of open public reasoning, which may or may not be reflected in the legal framework of a coun- try. In cases where it is not reflected in the legal framework, other ways of implementing these rights are through public recognition, agitation and monitoring. This again strengthens the role and responsibility of non-state actors in the human rights debate. Russell26 addresses the issue of the state’s obligation by referring to the fact that the Intern- ational Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights does not necessarily anticipate that all resources will come from the state. The implication was rather that the resources available from the broader society – in other words, public and private sectors – should be mobilised by the state. He also stresses the responsibilities of richer countries to supply funding to poorer countries, suggesting the international obligation of states. Secondly, many resource needs are centred on the misallocation of resources, eg expensive weapons instead of food security. The misallocation problem could be solved by a reordering of the state’s priorities. Thirdly, coun- tries facing severe resource constraints can focus on progressive realisation by developing plans that states its obligations over time. Fourthly, the state has an obligation to ensure that rights are not violated. Although these solutions sound feasible, all these suggestions predominantly still focus on the central role of the state decision-making process and do not allow for partic- ipatory development on a broader scale. In addressing the issue of the state’s responsibility within the broader framework of human development and the links with human rights, the United Nations through its Human Develop- ment Report27 suggests that, although a shift is evident from state to non-state actors, the state still has the responsibility to strengthen its policies and social arrangements, respectively, in securing human freedoms. On the policy front, the state has an obligation to implement poli- cies that help realise social and economic rights, especially for the most deprived. This must, however, be based on a participatory process and be transparent. The state’s social arrange- ments should be effected through norms, institutions, legal frameworks and an enabling eco- nomic environment. In addressing the norms issue, the state has the responsibility to promote awareness of human rights by building and promoting these through press freedom, human rights education in schools, etc. The state has the obligation to ensure that appropriate institu- tions are in place to support certain human rights (eg children’s rights) that cannot be guaran- teed without strong and effective institutions. States also have the first obligation to participate in the international rights regime and to establish legal frameworks. Finally, the state is obli- gated to create an economic environment that supports human rights. It should ensure that eco- nomic growth is pro-poor, pro-rights and sustainable. A number of related approaches have developed to support the notion that the state’s accountability should be expanded to include non-state actors. Heller28 presented the International Monetary Fund’s perspective when he concludes that social justice is far better achieved when those directly involved reveal their own values and put them together. This per- spective is more inclusive and allows for participatory development. Smith, 29 on the future of the international dimension of human rights, remarked that the responsibility of the realisation of human rights has to be extended outside the nation-state domain. Non-governmental organ- 26 Brand & Russell (note 3 above) at 17. 27 UNDP (2000) 7, 8. 28 PS Heller ‘Wealth Creation and Social Justice: an IMF perspective’ (2003) Paper Presented at the World Council of Churches/World Bank/IMF Meeting, February 2003. 29 Smith (note 2 above) at 340. isations (NGOs), civil society and non-state agents all have a responsibility. These various role players in the funding chain of human rights are also emphasised by Hegarty and Leonard,30 who include the role and responsibility of the global economy, foreign aid agencies, the link between trade and human rights, corporate codes of conduct and the role of NGOs. The involvement of non-state actors in supporting the state’s accountability in the human rights debate is, within the context of the human development framework, mutually reinforc- ing. In the 2000 Human Development Report31 various examples of the mutual participation of state and non-state actors are given. If the state ensures civil and political rights in general, poor people will be empowered to claim their social and economic rights. Ensuring freedom for NGOs and media and worker organisations can enhance the participation of poor people in decision-making processes and policy-making that affect their lives. In the same vein, the right to housing or education does not imply a right to free services or to a state handout. These are claims to social arrangements and policies that promote access to these rights through both the market (housing) and the state (free primary education). Worldwide public spending on social and economic rights is inadequate and unevenly distributed. Faster economic growth is needed to generate more resources to support social and economic justice. But, within the context of the human development framework, economic growth on its own is not enough. It has to be accompanied by transparent and participatory policy reforms that are aimed at channelling funds into poverty eradication and human development. On the international front the state’s responsibility to support and ensure human rights and human development is expanding. Apart from strengthening regional initiatives for human rights, individual states should also embark collectively on continuous efforts for peacemaking and peacekeeping. Individual states, in their responsibility through development cooperation in the form of aid flows, debt relief, access to trade and financial flows, and ensuring stability in the global economy, can all support the full realisation of rights in the poorest and least devel- oped countries of the world. Again, non-state actors such as multinational corporations are also accountable and have an obligation to raise the standard of human rights. IV Conclusion The fiscal implications of social and economic rights are firmly embedded in political ideolo- gies and the subsequent role of the state. This has clearly being shown in the changing rights framework, where the first shift occurred from the right side of the spectrum, which proposed no formal entrenchment of social and economic rights, to the extreme left side of the human rights spectrum, where the state has the sole responsibility to ensure social and economic jus- tice. However, over the past decade the second shift, which has been classified as the rights rev- olution, took place in the shift from the extreme left of the spectrum to a more centre-left approach with implications for the structure of the human rights framework as well as the state. The analysis reveals that social and economic rights have increased in importance since the early 1990s. This trend, as well as the inclusion of third-generation rights, blurred the previous artificial division between first-, second- and third-generation rights to form a broader concern with all rights. Coupled with the broader and extended redefinition of the concepts of devel- Fiscal Implications of Social and Economic Justice 177 30 A Hegarty & S Leonard Human Rights. An Agenda for the 21st Century (1999). 31 UNDP (note 27 above) at 8, 9. 1 7 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E opment, this led to convergence of the human rights agenda and the human development agen- da, in both concept and action, including the notion that they are mutually reinforcing. This convergence has extended the leftist state-centred model of accountability to a more centre-left approach where the state’s responsibility changed to include non-state actors. Another impor- tant trend is the increased importance of the state’s obligation beyond national borders. The changing framework of human rights discussed in this chapter is based upon the latest approaches as seen in the literature and theory of social and economic justice. However, it is important to note that, despite these continuous attempts to address these dilemmas, they have not so far been completely resolved. Of course, a theory of human rights can and should leave room for continuous discussion, disputations and arguments. The Historical Development of the Modern South African Health-Care System: From Privilege to Egalitarianism* C H A R L E S N G W E N A Professor, Department of Constitutional Law and Legal Philosophy, University of the Free State I Introduction This article seeks to explore the extent to which equity as a notion of fairness in access to health care has been integrated into the South African health-care system in recent history. The article discusses the main legislative and policy instruments that have shaped the South African health- care system. It begins with an analysis of the main pillars of the Public Health Act of 19191 and includes discussion on more recent developments, including the National Health Act.2 The arti- cle also comments on court cases that impact on equity in access to health care, including Minister of Health v Treatment Action Campaign.3 The point of departure is the ideal of creating a health-care system that strives for egalitarianism in respect of access to health-care services. It will be submitted that the Public Health Act of 1919 bequeathed to the country a system that was fragmented, dysfunctional, and above all, lacking in egalitarian values. Attempts to radically reform the Public Health Act through instruments such as the National Health Act of 19774 failed to change a system that was biased towards urban, curative and hospital-based care. Moreover, the intensification of racial segregation during apartheid and the privatisation of health-care services served to accentuate inequality in access to health care. It was not until the democratisation of South Africa that the health-care system began in earnest to trans- form towards universal access. At a policy level, the White Paper on Transformation of the Health System in South Africa (1997)5 stands as a beacon of change, with its emphasis on primary health care for all. At the level of fundamental law, the Constitution6 acknowledges access to health care. The National Health Act seeks to put on statutory footing the institutional framework for universal access to health care. * This article is based on a paper delivered at the Conference of the Southern African Society of Legal Historians at Stellenbosch University from 15–17 January 2003. The article first appeared in (2004) 37 De Jure 290-312 and is reprinted here (with minor changes) with the kind permission of C Ngwena and De Jure, the editor of De Jure and Lexis-Nexis Butterworths. 1 36 of 1919. 2 Act 61 of 2003. 3 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC). 4 63 of 1977. 5 GG 17910 of 1997-04-16. 6 Constitution of the Republic of South Africa Act 108 of 1996 (the Constitution) supplanting the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa Act 200 of 1993 (the interim Constitution). 1 8 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E II Equity in Access to Health Care Margolis is correct to say that merely appealing to notions of justice or fairness has inherent limitations in that any theory of justice or fairness is, ultimately, a human construct.7 A theory of justice cannot, by itself, establish a conclusive case for a desired outcome, and so it is with the notion of equity. Equity is a notion of justice. Much like other notions of justice, such as equality, it does not admit a single meaning. Its ultimate complexion depends on the ideologi- cal leanings of the interpreter. Thus, any notion of justice is necessarily a value judgement. In the context of access to health care, equity means different things to different interpreters. The notion of a right of access to health care is a contested right, not least at the level of philo- sophical theory and political ideology. In South Africa and elsewhere, though a number of diverse contractarian theories have been invoked when addressing the issue of access to health care, two main standpoints are dis- cernible, namely libertarianism and egalitarianism. In one sense, there is unity between these two positions in that they both converge on the desirability of achieving justice, and each pur- ports to offer a coherent view of life. At the same time, the two positions are characterised by pivotal points of contrast and opposition, not only in respect of conceptions of justice, but also in the delineation of the parameters of state vis-à-vis private-sector provision of health care. To classical libertarians, equitable access to health care might mean no more than treating peo- ple equally by desisting from unfair discrimination on the conventional prohibited grounds such as race, gender or sexual orientation.8 It usually means minimal state interference in the delivery of health care and the removal of state impediments such as the deregulation of the state health-care system in order to allow access to private health care.9 In this classic libertarian sense, equity is not synonymous with granting access to health care on the basis of need, or imposing an obligation on the state to take primary responsibility for the provision of health-care services to everyone. As Rhodes points out, the assumptions in classical liberal theory are that individuals are nor- mally responsible for their health and that they ought to be able to make their own health trans- actions in a free market.10 Those that are more affluent are able to purchase greater privileges because they deserve them, so it is argued. However, even the most ardent advocates of free markets do not dispute that the state has not only a role, but also a duty to discharge in respect of provision of health care. It is conceded, for example, that the state has an obligation to pre- vent and combat epidemics.11 The modern industrial state has, itself, contributed to many con- ditions that impact adversely on health such as environmental degradation and soaring crime. It has never been seriously argued by libertarians that the state should divest itself of all respon- sibility in these areas. What classical libertarians object to however, is a collectivist approach to equality where all groups are entitled to expect, as of right, a minimum standard of socio-eco- nomic goods, including health care.12 To egalitarians, however, equity is a more exacting concept.13 Much of the egalitarian con- 7 J Margolis ‘The Rights of Man’ (1978) 4 Social Theory and Practice 423. 8 D Feldman Civil Liberties and Human Rights in England and Wales (1993) at 901–902; HT Engelhardt ‘Rights to Health Care: A Critical Appraisal’ (1979) 4 Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 113. 9 Feldman (note 8 above); Engelhardt (note 8 above). 10 RP Rhodes Health Care Politics, Policy and Distributive Justice (1992) 19. 11 Rhodes (note 10 above) at 20. 12 Engelhardt (note 8 above). 13 RM Green ‘Health Care and Justice in Contract Perspective’ in RM Veatch & R Branson (eds) Ethics and Health Policy (1976) at 111–126. ception of access to health care was drawn substantially from Rawls’s theory of justice.14 According to Rawls, an individual in the original position’ makes his or her decisions behind a ‘veil of ignorance’. Acting out of rationality rather than altruism, the individual will try to max- imise his or her life chances by choosing universal political liberties so as not to risk the possi- bility of ills such as oppression, grinding poverty and so on. Such an individual will try to pro- tect equality of opportunity and, thus, secure for himself or herself minimum primary goods. While Rawls did not specifically list the provision and organisation of health care among the primary goods that an individual in the original position would require in order to enjoy equal- ity of opportunity, proponents of his theory of justice have done so. Perhaps the most persua- sive exponent in this connection has been Daniels.15 Daniels’s contribution to an egalitarian conception of access to health care has been to extend Rawls’s theory of justice to health care.16 Daniels has adapted Rawls’s principle of equality of opportunity into a principle of ‘normal opportunity range’. Daniels’s central premise is that if an acceptable theory of justice includes a principle for fair opportunity, then health care institutions and, perforce, health care policy and practice, should be among the goods governed by such a principle.17 According to Daniels, for any given society, there is a ‘normal opportunity range’ which com- prises of the ‘array of life plans reasonable to pursue within given conditions obtaining in socie- ty’.18 The resources of a society must be organised in such a way as to allow everyone to attain a normal opportunity range. Disease, most certainly, impairs in a fundamental manner the opportu- nity of an individual relative to the the normal opportunity range in a society governed by the prin- ciple of fair equality of opportunity.19 Access to health care, thus, becomes an essential prerequi- site, or a primary good in terms of indispensability to the attainment of the normal opportunity range for a given society. In practical terms, the right to exercise a normal opportunity range trans- lates into a right to a minimum, decent level of health care. There should be no obstacles – finan- cial, racial, sexual, geographical, and so on – to access to care as long as health needs are present. Of course, Daniels has not been without critics. Buchanan, for example, says that one of the more significant difficulties with Daniels’s ‘normal opportunity range’ and array of life-plans reasonable to pursue’ is that they are open to different interpretations.20 Buchanan contends that it is not clear for whom a life plan must be reasonable. If subjective view is taken, given different abilities and skills in any given society, some individuals might end up with claims that are so strong as to be unsustainable to the extent that resources are finite. Equally, Buchanan says that if an objective view is taken, what is reasonable for everyone might be too modest as to be insufficient to provide a basic for a substantive universal right to health care. In response to his critics, Daniels concedes that whilst the notion of normal opportunity range is not unas- sailable, it is, nonetheless, workable.21 According to Daniels, each society can construct for Historical Development of the SA Health-Care System 181 14 J Rawls A Theory of Justice (1972). 15 N Daniels ‘Health Care Needs and Distributive Justice’ (1981) 10 Philosophy and Public Affairs 146-179. 16 Daniels (note 15 above) at 163-168. 17 Daniels (note 15 above) 160-161. 18 Daniels (note 15 above) 158. 19 Daniels (note 15 above) 159. 20 A Buchanan ‘The Right to a Decent Minimum of Health Care’ (1984) 13(1) Philosophy and Public Affairs 55-78. See also L Stern ‘Opportunity and Health Care: Criticims and Suggestions’ (1983) 8(4) Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 339-361; J Moskop ‘Rawslian Justice and a Human Rights to Health Care’ (1983) 8(4) Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 329-338. 21 N Daniels ‘A Reply to Stern Critics and a Remark on Health Care Rights’ (1983) 8 Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 363-371. 1 8 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E itself its objective normal opportunity range. The range will be influenced by the key features of that society such as its stage of socio-economic development, material wealth, technological development and important cultural facts.22 Notwithstanding the criticisms of Daniels’ normal opportunity range and any of its inherent shortcomings, it is, nonetheless, a theoretical approach that has resonance with the egalitarian underpinnings of rights concerning health under international human rights law. As will become apparent in the ensuing discussion, the consequent duty upon the state to provide a decent minimum level of health care under human rights law is society-relative rather than abstract. It is not conceived in a vacuum. Rather, it allows for the decent minimum to be pegged flexibly so that as the particular society becomes more affluent, the minimum floor is com- mensurately adjusted upwards. Individuals will be free to purchase health care. The state is not put under a duty to provide everyone with the best available health care. Instead, the duty upon the state is limited to what is affordable for that society. An egalitarian conception of access to health care goes beyond the Aristotelian minimal princi- ple of justice in that it means much more than merely desisting from unfair discrimination or allow- ing for choice in health care. It means, at the very least, developing a health-care system that is responsive to need rather than the ability to pay.23 It also means maximal rather than minimal state interference in the provision of health care, with the state assuming primary responsibility for the provision of health care.24 Access to health care is conceived as a communal or social good that should be determined by need rather than life’s arbitrary lottery of birth, natural endowment, socio- economic status or historical circumstances. Health care should be distributed not merely on the basis of what is wanted or desired, but according to the basic needs for a worthwhile human life.25 It is to this egalitarian notion of equity that this article subscribes. It must be emphasised at the outset that equity does not imply the elimination of all differ- ences in health or the guaranteeing of equal health outcomes. Indeed, this would be an impos- sible goal to achieve since health-care services are but one of several health determinants. Genetic factors, income, housing, nutrition, water, sanitation, education and the general envi- ronment arguably impact to a greater extent on health outcomes than the mere provision of health-care services.26 Rather, the aim behind equity is to ensure that everyone has a fair oppor- tunity to access one of the determinants of health as part of the enjoyment of equality, freedom and human dignity in a democratic and caring society. Without access to health care one can- not effectively make autonomous choices, including realising one’s potential in a free society.27 For the greater part of the 20th century, it has been primarily moral philosophers, sociolo- gists, and health care providers and professionals that have imprinted egalitarian notions of equity into the provision of health care.28 Lately, however, human rights experts and activists have begun to champion egalitarian notions of health care.29 A human rights approach to health care has developed, not least on account of the emergence of socio-economic rights as tangible rights that are different in kind but have the same status as conventional civil or polit- 22 Daniels (note 15 above) 158. 23 HCJ Van Rensburg Health Care in South Africa: Structure and Dynamics (1992) at 364–370. 24 Van Rensburg (note 23 above). 25 W Landman ‘Appropriate Health Care as a Human Right’ in A Van Niekerk (ed) Health Care as Human Right (1993) at 36–71. 26 P Townsend et al The Black Report and the Health Divide (1990) at 104–106 and 286–305. 27 Landman (note 25 above) at 37–40. 28 Van Rensburg (note 23 above) at 352–403. 29 BCA Toebes The Right to Health as a Human Right in International Law (1999) at 3–36. ical rights. The right to health now enjoys the status of an international human right. The most important international instrument in terms of acknowledging, as well as expounding, the right to health is article 12 of the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (ICESCR).30 Article 12 doubtlessly subscribes to equity in an egalitarian sense.31 Under article 12, state parties acknowledge the right of everyone to enjoy the highest attainable standard of physical and mental health. In General Comment 14 the Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (Committee on ESCR), the organ responsible for monitoring state com- pliance with socio-economic rights, has put a gloss on the meaning and content of article 12.32 The Committee on ESCR concedes that there are limitations insofar as realising the right to health is concerned. The right to health cannot be equated with a right to be healthy.33 Indeed, the state can- not guarantee health. The right to health does not imply guaranteeing all the services that are avail- able. The notion of the highest attainable standard of health must necessarily take into account the individual’s biological and socio-economic preconditions and the resources of the state.34 Not- withstanding these limitations, the provision of health-care facilities, goods and services are an important determinant of health. Health care must, thus, be dispensed on an equitable basis. In this regard, the Committee on ESCR posits four requirements that must be met.35 Firstly, health care must be available.36 Public health and health-care facilities, goods and services must be available to all in sufficient quantity, including the underlying determinants of health such as safe and potable drinking water and adequate sanitation facilities. Secondly, the facilities, goods and services must be accessible.37 It is this dimension, more than any other, that underscores the notion of equity in the provision of health care. According to General Com- ment 14, accessibility has four overlapping dimensions, namely non-discrimination, physical accessibility, economic accessibility and information accessibility.38 Non-discrimination means providing health care without discrimination on any of the pro- hibited grounds. Physical accessibility means that the facilities, goods and services must be with- in safe physical reach of everyone, especially vulnerable groups. Economic accessibility means health care should be affordable for all. The General Comment explicitly says that payment for health-care services must be based on the principle of equity to ensure that health-care services are affordable for all, including socially disadvantaged groups.39 Furthermore, equity demands that poorer households should not be disproportionately burdened with health-care expenses as compared to richer households.40 Information accessibility means recognising and protect- Historical Development of the SA Health-Care System 183 30 Adopted and opened for signature, ratification and accession by General Assembly Resolution 2200A (XXI) of 1966-12-16. The right to health is also found in other international instruments. Examples in this regard are: article 12 of the Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination Against Women (1979); article 24 of the Convention of the Rights of the Child (2002); and article 16 of the African Charter of Human and People’s Rights (1981). 31 A Chapman ‘Core Obligations Related to the Right to Health and their Relevance for South Africa’ (2002) in D Brand & S Russell (eds) Exploring the Core Content of Socio-Economic Rights: South African and International Perspectives (2002) at 35–60; Toebes (note 29 above) at 243–289. 32 Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights General Comment 14 UN ESCOR (2000) Doc no E/C 12/2000/4. 33 Par 8. 34 Par 9. 35 Par 12. 36 Par 12(a). 37 Par 12(b). 38 Ibid. 39 Ibid. 40 Ibid. 1 8 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E ing the right to seek, receive and impart information concerning health issues. A third requirement of an equitable health-care system under General Comment 14 is accept- ability.41 Provided health care should be ethically and culturally appropriate. It must be respect- ful of the culture of individuals, minorities, peoples and communities. The fourth requirement is quality.42 Health care must be scientifically and medically appropriate and of good quality. General Comment 14 is not only instructive because of its convergence with philosophical and sociological notions of egalitarianism in health-care provision,43 but also because of its apt- ness in terms of the notion of substantive equality under the South African Constitution. The Constitutional Court has ascribed to section 9 – the equality clause – an expansive and sub- stantive concept of equality that goes beyond the mere achievement of formal equality.44 In the context of access to health care, substantive equality means providing access to health care tak- ing social and historical circumstances into account. The lasting nature of structural inequality that apartheid, especially, created among different population groups in terms of differential and inequitable access to the determinants of health such as education, housing, employment and health care has also to be dealt with and redressed through restitution and other compen- satory means.45 As will be elaborated upon in a subsequent section, the commitment to sub- stantive equality in the sphere of health-care provision is based beyond a doubt on section 27 of the Constitution. It provides: (1) Everyone has the right to have access to – (a) health care services including reproductive health care; (b) sufficient food and water; and (c) social security, including, if unable to support themselves and their dependents, appropriate social assistance. (2) The state must take reasonable legislative and other measures, within its avail- able resources, to achieve a progressive realization of each of these rights. (3) No one may be refused emergency medical treatment.46 How has the modern South African health-care system fared in terms of guaranteeing equitable access? To borrow from the language of the Committee on ESCR’s interpretation of article 12 of the ICESCR, has South African health care been available, accessible, acceptable and of good quality? 41 Par 12(c). 42 Par 12(d). 43 According to Van Rensburg (note 23 above) at 364–365, writing from a sociological perspective, a social- ly accountable heath-care system should meet the following demands: availability (geographically, strategi- cally and logistically); appropriateness and relevance; acceptability (personally and socio-culturally); adapt- ability and flexibility; accessibility (meaning the annulment of geographical, financial, racial, political and other barriers) and affordability. 44 See eg City Council of Pretoria v Walker 1998 (2) SA 363 (CC) par 62; National Coalition for Gay & Lesbian Equality v Minister of Justice 2000 (2) SA 1 (CC) par 62; J De Waal, I Currie & G Erasmus The Bill of Rights Handbook (2002) at 200–201; C Albertyn & B Goldblatt ‘Facing the Challenge of Transformation: The Difficulties in the Development of an Indigenous Jurisprudence of Equality’ (1998) 14 SAJHR 248. 45 C Ngwena ‘Substantive Equality in South African Health Care: The Limits of the Law’ (2000) 4 Medical Law International 111 at 111 and 115. 46 Emphasis added. III The Genesis of the Modern Health-Care System: The Public Health Act of 1919 The Public Health Act of 1919 marked the beginning of a modern health-care system in South Africa.47 It was the first comprehensive legislative measure on health services for the Union of South Africa. The Act was intended to supplant colonial legislation. The main objective was to create a central or national authority for the provision and regulation of health-care services. The South Africa Act of 1909, which created the Union of South Africa and unified the four colonies as a single political entity, did not unify colonial health legislation and policy.48 Instead, it mere- ly effected a transfer of colonial powers and duties to provincial authorities. As a result, the pro- vision of health care remained fragmented, with no central authority to formulate or co-ordinate policy. Until 1919, the department of internal affairs had the responsibility of controlling the dis- trict surgeon system and institutions for the mentally ill and those afflicted with leprosy, and was therefore the only body with pretentions of being a central health authority.49 It is significant to note that prior to the Act, the health of the population and the availabili- ty of health care were not major social concerns or, for that matter, a primary responsibility of government. Individuals, with the assistance of their families, had to provide for their own health-care services.50 The public health facilities essentially catered only for serious illnesses or infectious diseases of an epidemic nature.51 There was no real organisational structure for ren- dering health care. The Act was the first legislation to define national responsibilities for pub- lic health. The impetus for change came with the influenza epidemic of 1918. The epidemic had high morbidity and mortality rates, killing an estimated 142 000 people.52 The epidemic unmasked the deficiencies of the prevailing health-care systems and underscored the need for the state to assume primary responsibility for health care and to reorganise health-care servic- es. The Public Health Act of 1919 was the response. In essence, the 1919 Act created a tripartite system. The first tier was a national department of public health responsible for the control of the following: contagious diseases and advance- ment of environmental health; district surgeon services; and institutions for the mentally ill and those afflicted with leprosy and tuberculosis. The second tier comprised provincial administra- tions. Provincial administrations were charged with establishing, maintaining and managing hospitals and other curative services. Local authorities were the third tier. They were conceived as agents of the department of public health and were responsible for controlling contagious diseases and environmental health. The 1919 Act had minimal success.53 According to Van Rensburg et al, the 1919 Act drew the lasting contours of a highly fragmented system of health provision that became not only the main characteristic, but also the fundamental problem, in the organisation and dispensation of South African health care.54 The 1919 Act chiefly failed because of the fragmented nature of Historical Development of the SA Health-Care System 185 47 Note 1 above. 48 Van Rensburg (note 23 above) at 59; see also C De Beer ‘A Forward View of the Health Services in South Africa’ (1976) 50 South African Medical Journal at 431. 49 Ibid. 50 JJN Cloete Administration of Health Services (1981) at 2–3; BE Leech ‘The Right of the HIV-Positive Patient to Medical Care: An Analysis of Costs of Providing Medical Treatment’ (1993) 9 SAJHR 39 at 43. 51 Ibid. 52 Van Rensburg (note 23 above) at 59. 53 Van Rensburg (note 23 above) at 60. 54 Ibid. 1 8 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E the tripartite system. There was little co-ordination between the department of public health and local authorities. Each tier tended to function at the exclusion of the other, at the expense of providing a broader spectrum of co-ordinated services. There was polarisation between cur- ative and preventative services. Provincial authorities unduly preoccupied themselves with the provision of curative hospital-based care. Community health or primary health was virtually neglected. In part, the 1919 Act failed because it had not been conceived to render universal comprehensive care. It could not stand up to the demands of the South African society in the 1930s and 1940s especially. The Great Depression, the poverty among Blacks as well as Whites, large scale industrialisation, rapid urbanisation, expansion of the black labour class, desperate housing conditions, unhygienic living conditions and widespread malnutrition expressed them- selves partly in escalating conditions of poor health.55 Tubercular epidemics, nutritional defi- ciency diseases, venereal disease, high levels of morbidity and high infant and maternal mor- tality among all sectors of the population indicated the Act’s deficiencies. Indeed, it was these shortcomings that spurred government into appointing commissions of inquiry to investigate and ameliorate harsh social conditions. In the health sphere, the most significant commission of inquiry was the National Health Services Commission, the Gluckman Commission, that was appointed in 1942.56 IV Reforms: The Gluckman Commission The Gluckman Commission was set up to inquire into both the provision of an organised national service, and the necessary administrative, legislative and financial measures for such a service. The Commission was admirably loyal to its brief. In 1944 it reported its findings and recommended the reorganisation of the health service in the light of deteriorating health indi- cators and social conditions. The Commission sought to reorganise health services and ‘bring these services within reach of all sections of the population, according to need, and without regard to race, colour, means or station in life’.57 Though the Gluckman Commission eschewed the language of entitlement and rights, its egalitarian thrust is unmistakable. This is all the more remarkable given the Commission was operating in a society that was highly stratified, not least in terms of race, and that the language of health as a human right had yet to take root even in Western liberal democracies, let alone in South Africa. At an international level, it was not until 55 Van Rensburg (note 23 above) at 60; R Packard White Plague, Black Labor: Tuberculosis and the Political Economy of Health and Disease in South Africa (1989) at 126–193; A Jeeves ‘Public Health and Epidemiology in the Era of South Africa’s VD Pandemic of the 1930s and 1940s’ paper read at AIDS in Context International Conference held at the University of the Witwatersrand from 4–7 April 2001 (copy on file with author). 56 D Gluckman Report of the National Health Services Commission (1944). Prior to the Gluckman Com- mission the government had from time to time appointed a committee to inquire into various matters per- taining to the provision of health-care services. The Committee of Inquiry regarding Public Hospitals and Kindred Institutions of 1925 looked into the deterioration in the health of the black population in rural and urban areas. The Committee of Inquiry on Medical Training for Natives of 1928 looked into the state sub- sidy for and training of black medical personnel and the establishment of health units in rural areas as a response to the deteriorating health of the black population. The Committee of National Health Insurance of 1936 inquired into the feasibility of introducing a national health insurance scheme. However, the find- ings and recommendations of these committees were never acted on by government: Van Rensburg (note 23 above) at 61. 57 Gluckman Commission (note 56 above) at 8. 1946 that the notion of access to health as a universal right was first articulated, when the World Health Organisation in the preamble to its constitution proclaimed that the ‘enjoyment of the highest attainable standard of health is one of the fundamental rights of which every human being, without distinction of race, religion, political belief, economic or social condi- tions’, is entitled.58 The Commission found a health system that was fragmented and uncoordinated. The system unduly emphasised institutional care and ignored preventive and community-based care. It suf- fered from deprivation, especially for Blacks, with the deprivation more acute in rural reserves. The private sector was a distorting element. Not only was private health care unaffordable for the majority of people, it was also geographically inaccessible as private practitioners predom- inantly positioned themselves in cities and major towns. The recommendations of the Commission were, in essence, a blueprint for an egalitarian health-care system. In the main, the Commission recommended the establishment of a uni- fied single health authority, with the state assuming primary responsibility for the provision of health care. Significantly, services would be free and financed out of general taxation. Services were to be decentralised. Community health services would be established to bring health-care services close to people and to reduce dependence on curative care. Even more radically, the Commission recommended the phasing out altogether of private practice on account of its distorting effect. The Commission was not oblivious to the fact that health is not an outcome of the mere provision of health-care services alone and that other socio-eco- nomic factors had an even greater impact on health. As part of augmenting the provision of health-care services, the Commission called for vast improvements in nutrition, housing and health education. According to the Commission, health-care services alone could not make up for the deficiencies of the socio-economic system.59 In short, the Commission called for fundamental reform. Regrettably, however, the substance of the Commission’s recommendations was never imple- mented by the incumbent government, except for a limited programme of establishing commu- nity health centres.60 A number of factors conspired to ensure the demise of the Commission’s recommendations. Initially the recommendations fell victim to apathy and procrastination on the part of the Smuts government.61 The Smuts government was unwilling to encroach upon provincial powers as part of the reorganisation of services. Provinces in turn resisted change and were unwilling to relinquish their jurisdiction over curative institutions.62 The medical pro- fession also resisted change as it feared losing professional autonomy and the profits of private practice.63 However, the factor that dealt a mortal blow to the recommendations was the com- ing to power of the National Party in 1948. The recommendations were resolutely cast aside in the intensification of racial segregation under apartheid. De Beer aptly summed up the fate of the Gluckman Commission when he said: Historical Development of the SA Health-Care System 187 58 The Constitution of the World Health Organisation was opened for signature on 1946-07-22 and entered into force on 1948-04-07; Toebes (note 29 above) 31. 59 Gluckman Commission (note 56 above) at 27. 60 An attempt was made to implement the recommendations of the Gluckman Commission through the National Health Act of 1946. The most tangible outcome of this Act was the establishment of 50 commu- nity health centres: Van Rensburg (note 23 above) at 63. 61 Ibid. 62 Ibid. 63 Ibid. 1 8 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E The tragedy is not that the proposals of the Gluckman Commission were not imple- mented. The tragedy is that they could not possibly have been implemented. There is simply no way that a society built on division, oppression, and exploitation could accommodate a health service premised on unity, equality, and the elevation of the needs of all above the needs of the privileged elite.64 Thus, nothing short of a fundamental radical transformation of the prevailing political econo- my was needed if the recommendations of the Gluckman Commission were to be adopted and implemented by the government of the day. V Apartheid and South African Health Care The Medical Research Council described the South African health-care system during apartheid as a ‘bureaucratic entanglement of racially and ethnically fragmented services; wasteful and neglectful of the health of more than two thirds of the population’.65 During apartheid, income, geographical location and, most importantly, race became the arch determinants of the quanti- ty and quality of health care received by the populace.66 State-ordained racially-based inequal- ity in access to health care became the defining characteristic of the South African health-care system. It bears mentioning, however, that racial segregation in the organisation of health services has a long history and did not commence in 1948 with official apartheid. Since the colonisa- tion of South Africa, health services evolved along the lines of racial segregation with a sys- tematic bias towards Whites.67 What was done during apartheid, however, was to take the seg- regation in the form of separate and unequal access to services to extreme levels. According to Van Rensburg and Benatar, apartheid has been the most important historical force in the moulding of both the South African health-care system and the health of the people of South Africa in modern times.68 During apartheid, the provision of health facilities, the allocation of public funds, and the deployment of health-care personnel were stratified according to race. As in other socio-eco- nomic spheres that were commanded by the state, the health-care system became a tool for shoring up white supremacy.69 Whites were the privileged class and Blacks the worst provided for in terms of access to health-care facilities. Coloureds and Indians occupied an intermediate position. Per capita expenditure on health during apartheid shows that Whites received four times as much as Africans from the public health sector budget.70 64 C de Beer ‘Explaining the Present: Why Health Services do not meet the Health Needs of the Population’ in A Zwi & WB Saunders (eds) Towards Health Care for All (1985) at 59. 65 Medical Research Council Changing Health in South Africa: Towards New Perspectives in Research (1991) at 7. 66 Van Rensburg (note 23 above) at 56–58. 67 HCJ van Rensburg & SR Benatar ‘The Legacy of Apartheid in Health and Health Care’ (1993) 24 SA Journal of Sociology 99 at 99. 68 Ibid at 99. 69 M Price ‘Health Care as an Instrument of Apartheid Policy in South Africa’ (1986) 1 Health Policy and Planning 158 at 158. 70 DE McIntyre & RE Dorrington ‘Trends in the Distribution of South African Health Care Expenditure’ (1990) 78 SAMJ 125 at 125; HCJ van Rensburg ‘South African Health Care in Change’ (1991) 22 SA Journal of Sociology 1 at 5. Apart from prescribing inequitable access to health-care services, the effects of apartheid were also manifest in racial discrepancies in health status. The burden of morbidity and mor- tality was disproportionately carried by Blacks and Coloureds.71 However, it is important not to ascribe differential health status to segregated health-care services alone. As alluded to ear- lier, health status is not merely an outcome of health care, but an outcome of a multiplicity of socio-economic factors. Racial discrepancies in health status are attributable to differential access not only to health-care services, but also to other goods reliant on socio-economic sta- tion such as nutrition, employment, housing and sanitation, which were similarly shaped by apartheid. The racial fragmentation of services was accentuated by the homelands policy, which creat- ed bantustans, and by the tricameral Constitution of 1983, which established ethnically based departments of health.72 The homelands policy established ten separate health authorities for the bantustans. The tricameral Constitution added three “own affairs” health authorities for Coloureds, Indians and Whites. The racial segregation of services also accentuated the urban- rural chasm in the provision of services. Health-care services were prioritised for Whites who were concentrated in the urban areas. For Africans in the rural areas, access to health-care serv- ices was virtually unattainable.73 Attempts to reform the health-care system were submerged by the overarching apartheid superstructure, which consciously ensured that the primary beneficiaries of any reform would be first and foremost Whites, with Indians and Coloureds occupying somewhat intermediate positions. The most significant attempt to reform the system bequeathed by the 1919 Act was the passing of the Health Act 63 of 1977. The Act was intended to repeal the 1919 Act and provide for the rendition of health services to the inhabitants of South Africa. The Act created new structures, in particular the National Health Policy Council, which had the responsibility of formulating national policy on health and co-ordinating services. The Act’s professed inten- tion was to provide, through the department of health and welfare, ‘comprehensive health serv- ices for the population of the Republic of South Africa’.74 However, it failed dismally in this regard, not least because it preoccupied itself with the provision of health-care services to White South Africa only. It was not only race which compromised the 1977 Act, but also deregulation of the health sector in the 1970s.75 Privatisation gave the private health sector a lasting and dominant posi- tion in the provision of health care in South Africa. Private-sector health care, with its exorbi- tant fees, served only twenty percent of the population and thus accentuated inequalities in access to health care.76 Historical Development of the SA Health-Care System 189 71 From 1980 to 1985 infant mortality was 13% for Whites, 18.9% for Indians, 56% for Coloureds and 82% for Africans. Life expectancy was 66.8 for Whites, 63.1 for Indians, 55.4 for Coloureds and 55.1 for Africans: Van Rensburg & Benatar (note 67 above) at 106. 72 M Price Health Policy and Planning (1986 ) at 148. 73 Van Rensburg & Benatar (note 67 above) at 104. 74 Sec 14(a) of the Act. 75 Van Rensburg (note 23 above) at 79–83; HCJ an Rensburg & A Fourie ‘Privatisation of South African Health Care: In Whose Interest?’ (1988) 11 Curationis 1 at 1. 76 Ibid. 1 9 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E VI Reforms in the Democratic Era (A) POLICY AND LEGISLATION Since the advent of the new constitutional dispensation, health-care reforms have been truly anchored in equity, not least because the achievement of substantive equality is a constitution- al imperative. Moreover, the Constitution recognises the right of every person to have access to health care.77 The state has an obligation to deploy resources at its disposal in order to achieve on a progressive basis the realisation of the right to have access to health care.78 To use the lan- guage of the Committee on ESCR, once again, the goal now is to achieve a health-care system that is available, accessible, acceptable and of a good quality. As stated in the introduction, the White Paper for Transformation of the Health System in South Africa (White Paper) has provided the arch policy blueprint for egalitarian health care at a policy level.79 It was explicitly aimed at ‘promoting equity by developing a single, unified health system’.80 It espoused the goal of making primary health care available as the health-care system’s point of entry for all people, irrespective of race, means and geographical locality.81 It sought to bridge the urban-rural divide and the disparities in economic means by, inter alia, ‘focusing on the rural, peri-urban and urban poor and the aged, with an emphasis on vulnerable groups’.82 The philosophy underpinning the White Paper is not only a product of constitutional imper- atives, but also a reflection of acceptance of international consensus on the equitable provision of health-care services. The concept of primary health care, which is all pervasive in the White Paper, is largely a progeny of the international authority on health, the World Health Organisation (WHO).83 The WHO developed the concept in the 1970s with the aim of ensur- ing that everyone gains access to health care necessary for leading a ‘socially and economically productive life’.84 The concept was given a boost in 1978 by the international conference of pri- mary health care that was held in Alma Ata.85 In the Declaration of Alma Ata, which was adopted at this conference, primary health care is defined in the following terms: Primary health care is essential care based on practical, scientifically sound and socially acceptable methods and technology made universally accessible to individu- als and families in the community though their full participation and at a cost that the community can afford to maintain at every stage of their development in the spir- it of self-reliance and self-determination. It forms an integral part of both the coun- try’s health system of which it is the central function and main focus, and of the over- all social economic development of the community. It is the first level of contact of 77 Sec 27 of the Constitution. 78 Sec 27(2) of the Constitution. 79 Par I above. 80 White Paper at 10. 81 White Paper at 10. 82 White Paper at 14. 83 World Health Organisation Global Strategy for Health for All by the Year 2000 (1981). Note, however, that according to Toebes (note 29 above) 34 the idea of primary health care was not entirely borne out of WHO. As far back as in 1931 and in 1937, the Health Organisation of the League of Nations had, at two health conferences on rural health, promoted the idea of primary health services for all. 84 Ibid. 85 Toebes (note 29 above) at 35. individuals, the family and the community with the health system bringing health as close as possible to where people live and work, and constitutes the first element of a continuing health care process.86 Thus, the cardinal idea behind the principle of primary health care is that there are health-care services that are essential or basic to the socio-economic survival and development of individuals and communities. Consequently, such health care ought to be within the reach of everyone and means and distance should not be obstacles. It is for government to ensure the accessibility of health care. Moreover, there must be democratic involvement of the community in the planning and implementation of health care so as to ensure acceptability of the services that are rendered. As part of the promotion of equity, and implementation of the primary health-care system, a redistribution of public health resources is underway.87 The historical bias towards urban-based curative institutions is being reversed in favour of equitable geographical allocations of health resources and facilities. The move is geared towards providing health facilities in areas that have been historically deprived. In this regard, a massive clinic-building system is underway through- out the country to implement primary health care.88 A complementary development has been the implementation of the District Health System (DHS) as a way of not only decentralising, but also democratising health-care services.89 The DHS is challenging the legacy of the Public Health Act of 1919, which bequeathed a fragmented and dysfunctional health-care system. There have also been numerous legislative interventions with a view to facilitating the reali- sation of equitable access to health care.90 The egalitarian organisation of the South African health system has, at long last, been placed on a statutory footing with the passing in 2004 of the National Health Act.91 The Act is built on an edifice of the achievement of substantive equality in the provision of health care. In its preamble, the Act recognises the socio-economic injustices and the inequities of health services in the past. It seeks to comply with the state’s con- stitutional obligation to take reasonable, legislative and other measures within its means to achieve the progressive realisation of the right of everyone to have access to health-care servic- es under section 27 of the Constitution. The Act subscribes to co-operative governance and decentralised management of health services in which national government, provinces, munic- ipalities and health districts collectively address questions of health policy and delivery of health care services.92 As part of the democratisation of health services, the Act provides for the involvement of the community in the governance of health care services.93 Historical Development of the SA Health-Care System 191 86 At VI of the Declaration of Alma Ata. 87 HCJ Van Rensburg ‘Health and Health Care in South Africa in Transition: A Macro Perspective’ (1999) 31 Acta Academica 1 at 1; SR Benatar ‘Health Care Reform in the New South Africa’ (1997) 336 The New England Journal of Medicine 881 at 891. 88 Ibid. 89 Ibid. 90 Eg: In 1994 a presidential decree accorded pregnant mothers and children under 6 years entitlement to free health services; The Choice on Termination of Pregnancy Act 92 of 1996 radically reformed abortion law to, inter alia, provide abortion on request in the first 12 weeks of pregnancy; the Medical Schemes Act 131 of 1998 outlawing unfair discrimination in the provision of health cover under medical schemes. Some pieces of legislation have engendered strong criticism or opposition. An example is the attempt by govern- ment to permit compulsory licencing and parallel importation of drugs through the Medicines and Related Substances Act 90 of 1997, that was met with vociferous opposition not only from the South African phar- maceutical industry but also by foreign conglomerates and many industrialised countries. 91 Note 2 above. 92 Preamble to the Act. 93 Section 31 of the National Health Act. 1 9 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E (B) JUDICIAL DECISIONS In the democratic era, courts have, by virtue of constitutional imperatives, begun to accord judicial confirmation to the egalitarian ethos that underpins access to health care in the new South Africa. A particularly welcome development in this regard is the relatively recent deci- sion of the Constitutional Court in Minister of Health v Treatment Action Campaign, where government was ordered to provide antiretroviral therapy at public health facilities on a uni- versal basis for the prevention of mother-to-child transmission of HIV.94 In this case, govern- ment policy of restricting the provision of Nevirapine (administered for the purpose of pre- venting the mother-to-child transmission of HIV) to eighteen pilot sites in the country was chal- lenged on the ground, inter alia, that it was contrary to section 27 of the Constitution.95 Government had sought to justify its decision on the grounds that it had to monitor the possi- ble side effects of Nevirapine so as to ensure the safety of the drug and that it was necessary to study the socio-economic and public health implications of providing the drug before develop- ing a universal comprehensive package of care. The government’s arguments failed before the Constitutional Court. In Treatment Action Campaign, the court drew from principles for the adjudication of socio- economic rights that had been developed earlier in Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom.96 In Grootboom, the court was concerned with whether a state housing policy and programme, inter alia, complied with the duties imposed upon the state by section 26 of the Constitution. Section 26 is analogous to section 27 in that both provisions guarantee access to a socio-economic good and require the state to take reasonable legislative and other meas- ures to achieve the progressive realisation of the right in question. Grootboom represents a holistic approach to the interpretation of socio-economic rights.97 Recourse to the jurispru- dence of the Committee on ESCR was crucial in dispelling the myth that socio-economic rights are intangible, unascertainable and unrealisable. Throughout the judgment, the court drew sus- tenance from the foundational values of the Constitution. Achieving substantive equality and protecting human dignity in the aftermath of a legacy of state-spawned gross inequality in access to housing were given due emphasis, as was the imperative to protect the most vulnera- ble and weakest in our society as part of the transformation of post-colonial and post-apartheid South Africa. In Grootboom, the court was of the view that although the respondent’s housing 92 Preamble to the Act. 93 Section 31 of the National Health Act. 94 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC). 95 Note that apart from sec 27 of the Constitution, there was also reliance on other provisions, especially at first instance, sec 7(2) which enjoins the state to respect, protect, promote and fulfil the rights in the Constitution; sec 10 which guarantees human dignity; sec 12(2)(a) which guarantees the right to bodily and psychological integrity including the right to make decisions about reproduction; sec 28(1)(c) which, inter alia, guarantees a child a right to basic health-care services; sec 195 which, inter alia, enjoins that public administration must be governed by the democratic values that are enshrined in the Constitution and that a high standard of professional ethics must be promoted and maintained, and sec 237 which provides that all constitutional obligations must be performed diligently without delay. 96 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC). 97 P de Vos ‘Grootboom, the Right of Access to Housing and Substantive Equality as Con- textual Fairness’ (2001) 13 SAJHR 258 at 258; S Liebenberg ‘The Right to Social Assistance: The Implications of Grootboom for Policy Reform in South Africa’ (2001) 13 SAJHR 232 at 232; J Sloth- Nielsen ‘The Right to Social Services, the Right to Social Security, and the Primary Prevention of Child Abuse in the Aftermath of Grootboom’ (2001) 13 SAJHR 210 at 224. programme was commendable in many respects, it did not pass constitutional muster because it did not accommodate the immediate needs of the poorest and, perforce, most vulnerable in our society.98 Thus Grootboom constitutes a triumph for the realisation of an egalitarian ethos. In Treatment Action Campaign, the court, taking its cue from Grootboom, demonstrated a bold willingness to impugn executive policy to the extent that the policy impacted on the respect, protection, promotion and fulfilment of fundamental rights in the Constitution. While the court conceded that the executive had constitutional pre-eminence in policy decision-making, the court did not at the same time interpret the doctrine of separation of powers as implying judicial abdi- cation on policy matters that impact on fundamental rights.99 Government had a positive duty to take reasonable legislative and other measures, with consideration of its available resources, to achieve the progressive realisation of the right of access to health-care services.100 The court was of the unanimous view that government policy was inconsistent with the faithful discharge of this duty. Government policy was inflexible.101 It denied 90 percent of mothers and their babies who relied on public health facilities the opportunity to access safe, life-saving therapy that was man- ifestly affordable to the state.102 The court was clearly aware that these mothers and consequently their children were indigent and unable to access private health-care facilities, where Nevirapine was available for a fee.103 In reaching this conclusion, the court also took cognisance of section 28 of the Constitution which guarantees children a package of rights, including a right to ‘basic health services’.104 According to the court, Nevirapine was ‘essential’ to the child.105 Without Nevirapine the life of the rights would be ‘most in peril’.106 Although Treatment Action Campaign was concerned only with the issue of access to anti- retroviral therapy for the prevention of mother-to-child transmission of HIV, it appears to have heralded positive changes in government policy towards the provision of antiretroviral therapy generally. For many years government policy has been to provide symptomatic treatment only for HIV/AIDS. Government had maintained that it could not afford the cost of antiretrovirals. However, in 2003, government announced that it was committed to the universal provision of antiretroviral therapy for people living with AIDS and set up a committee to plan and oversee the implementation of its commitment.107 South Africa has the highest number of people liv- ing with HIV/AIDS in a single country. It is estimated that 5.3 million people (approximately twelve and a half percent of the population) are living with AIDS.108 HIV/AIDS-related deaths account for 25 percent of all adult deaths.109 On account of costs, antiretroviral therapy has thus far been inaccessible to the majority of people living with HIV/AIDS, with a consequent toll on morbidity and mortality. There is little doubt that if the commitment to provide univer- Historical Development of the SA Health-Care System 193 98 Grootboom 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC) paras 44, 52, 56, 63, and 69. 99 Treatment Action Campaign 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC) paras 98–99. 100 Sec 27(2) of the Constitution. 101 Treatment Action Campaign 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC) par 80. 102 Par 98. 103 Par 79. 104 Sec 28(1)(c) of the Constitution. 105 Treatment Action Campaign 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC) par 78. 106 Par 78. 107 Department of Health Operational Plan for Comprehensive HIV and AIDS Care, Management and Treatment for South Africa (2003). 108 Department of Health National HIV and Syphilis Sero-Prevalence Survey of Women Attending Ante-Natal Clinics in South Africa in 2001 (2003). 109 RE Dorrington et al The Impact of HIV/AIDS on Adult Mortality in South Africa (2001) at 6. 1 9 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E sal access to antiretroviral therapy is implemented, it will go a long way towards redressing the lottery of income in determining access to life-saving therapy. It is not, however, suggested that the change in policy on antiretroviral therapy should be ascribed to Treatment Action Campaign. A number of factors came into play, including a gov- ernment-commissioned report, indicating that it was feasible to provide antiretroviral therapy in the public sector;110 political pressure brought to bear on government by civil society;111 sig- nificant lowering of the price of antiretroviral therapy by pharmaceutical multinational firms;112 and international commitments to permit developing countries facing dire HIV/AIDS pandemics to avail themselves of strategies such as parallel importation and compulsory licens- ing under the Agreement on Trade Related Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights without fear of economic reprisals from Western countries.113 What Treatment Action Campaign managed to do, however, was to facilitate the sustenance and intensification of the public debate on equi- table access to antiretroviral therapy in the media and other fora. It is important to appreciate that Treatment Action Campaign is not the only case in which the courts have dealt with a fundamental right impacting on access to health-care services. There are two earlier cases, B v Minister of Correctional Services114 and Soobramoney v Minister of Health, KwaZulu-Natal,115 where courts adjudicated on access to health care. Neither case can be regarded as particularly instructive on the development of principles that relate to equitable access to health-care services. In B four prisoners who were HIV-positive had been refused access to antiretroviral therapy by the department of correctional services on the ground of cost. Antiretroviral therapy had been prescribed for two of the prisoners. They sought an order before the High Court to require provision of antiretroviral therapy. They based their case on section 35(2)(e) of the Constitution, which guarantees a person in state incarceration a right to ‘adequate medical treatment’. The court held that the department had a duty to provide the therapy to only the two prisoners to whom it had been prescribed. A number of criticisms can be levelled at the B case. Much of the case dealt with determin- ing whether anti-retroviral therapy was within the ambit of adequate medical treatment, given its costliness. However, the court did not turn to international human rights jurisprudence for interpretive guidance on this point, except to observe that the term ‘adequate’ was relative and that its meaning could only be determined according to a given context, taking into account available resources. Notwithstanding the relative exorbitant price of antiretroviral therapy at the time and its inaccessibility to the majority of South Africans living with HIV/AIDS, the court was satisfied that the treatment the prisoners were seeking was no more than ade- quate.116 The case seemed to turn on the narrow point that the department of correctional serv- ices had pleaded lack of resources, but had failed to submit convincing supporting evidence. 110 J Kindra ‘AIDS: Ministers Revolt’ Mail & Guardian 2003-08-15 to 2003-08-21 at 2. 111 C Keeton ‘Turning Point for AIDS Treatment’ Sunday Times 2003-08-10 at 17. 112 Globally, the annual cost of antiretroviral therapy has fallen from about $12 000 to $300pp. 113 On 2003-08-30, the WTO agreed to permit developing countries badly affected by HIV/AIDS, tuberculo- sis, and malaria to import cheap generic drugs: C Kapp ‘World Trade Organisation Reaches Agreement on Generic Medicines’ (2003) 362 Lancet 807 at 807; N Courage ‘WTO Agreement Improves Access to Life- Saving Drugs’ The Lawyers Weekly 2003-09-26 at http://www.bereskinparr.ca/publications/art_html/biotech- wto-html. 114 1997 (6) BCLR 789 (C). 115 1998 (1) SA 765 (CC). 116 B v Minister of Correctional Services 1997 (6) BCLR 789 (C) par 60. Even if it is accepted that the court was correct in regarding antiretroviral therapy as adequate medical treatment within the meaning of section 35(2)(e), the order to provide antiretroviral therapy to only two of the applicants is problematic. As the judge observed, the overcrowding in prisons exacerbates the vulnerability of prisoners living with HIV to opportunistic infections, including tuberculosis and pneumonia.117 Overcrowding contributes significantly to neglect of hygiene, care and supervision. Over and above the overcrowding, there is stress, violence and malnutrition to contend with.118 South African prisons are characteristically violent places. Rape is rampant.119 It has been suggested that incarceration reduces the life expectancy of a person living with HIV by 50 percent by accelerating the infectious stage of the disease to full- blown AIDS.120 In 1999 a study conducted by a judicial inspectorate found that 90 percent of deaths of people who are incarcerated are AIDS-related.121 Voluntary as well as coerced sex in prisons adds significantly to HIV prevalence among male prisoners. It is estimated that 65 per- cent of male prisoners engage in homosexual activity.122 Even though prisoners have a higher morbidity and mortality rate from HIV/AIDS than their counterparts in the community, the court in B did not consider whether antiretroviral therapy would also constitute adequate treatment for other prisoners for whom it had not been pre- scribed, but were nonetheless seeking it on the ground that it had a prophylactic effect in peo- ple living with HIV/AIDS. Brand J rejected the claim of the prisoners for whom the therapy had not been prescribed on the ground that granting the order would amount to instructing med- ical doctors to prescribe the therapy.123 The judge erroneously equated granting an order of constitutional entitlement to antiretroviral therapy with obliging doctors to prescribe those entitlements. As shown by Treatment Action Campaign, it would have been possible for the court to grant a wider order to the effect that where antiretroviral therapy is medically indi- cated for prisoners living with HIV/AIDS, there is a constitutional duty to provide it on the part of the state, but subject to available resources. That way, the decision of the court would have assisted other prisoners falling in the same class as the successful applicants. It would have pro- vided clearer guidance to those doctors who are consulted by prisoners living with HIV/AIDS. The Soobramoney case concerns a man who was seeking to compel the respondent to pro- vide him with renal dialysis. He suffered from chronic renal failure. He had been receiving dial- ysis through private care, but his funds had run out. He sought to have dialysis provided to him, at state expense, by a renal unit of a state hospital. Otherwise he would have died. His request was declined. The renal unit could only meet 30 percent of the demand for renal dialysis. It could only provide renal dialysis to patients who were candidates for renal transplantation. Thus, it could only provide dialysis to those patients who needed it in the short term and not as life-long therapy. The applicant was not a candidate for transplantation. He suffered from ischaemic heart disease and was a diabetic with peripheral vascular disease. In the previous year, he had suffered a stroke. Though the applicant canvassed several grounds in support of his application, in the main, Historical Development of the SA Health-Care System 195 117 Par 54. 118 KC Goyer ‘HIV/AIDS in South African Prisons’ http://www.iss.co.za/Pubs/Monographs/ No79/Chap1.html accessed on 2004-01-18. 119 Ibid. 120 Ibid. 121 Ibid. 122 Ibid. 123 B v Minister of Correctional Services 1997 (6) BCLR 789 (C) par 37. 1 9 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E he contended that the respondent’s decision had infringed his right to life in terms of section 11 of the Constitution and his right not to be refused emergency medical treatment in terms of sec- tion 27(3). The court was of the opinion that the right to life argument was inappropriate as the Constitution provided explicitly for rights concerning access to health-care services. In respect of section 27(3), the court held that although the section was capable of being more broadly interpreted to include ongoing treatment for chronic conditions, it had a narrower meaning. It was not intended for a condition such as chronic renal failure. Instead it was intend- ed for a sudden catastrophe or unexpected trauma. In any event, the court was also of the view that even if chronic renal failure constituted an emergency, the state was not violating its obli- gations when it declined to provide renal dialysis, as its resources were limited. Although the applicant had not raised the issue, the court also took the opportunity to con- sider the application of section 27(1) and (2) to the facts of the case. The court suggested that these sections were more appropriate to the facts of the case than sections 11 or 27(3) of the Constitution. It was held, unanimously, that on account of scarcity of resources, it could not be said that the state had failed to discharge its section 27(2) obligations.124 For a number of reasons Soobramoney did not contribute much to the understanding of socio-economic rights.125 The outcome of the case itself was correct, given the prevailing scarci- ty of resources to provide life-long renal dialysis at a time when the state health sector could meet only 30 percent of the demand for renal dialysis.126 Under the guidelines that had been worked out by the state renal unit, priority was given to patients who were candidates for renal transplant and, thus, did not require life-long dialysis. Despite reaching the correct decision, the court was unduly restrictive in its interpretation of section 27(3). It had been argued by the appellant that section 11 of the Constitution was rel- evant to the interpretation of section 27(3) to the extent that refusal to provide renal dialysis meant that the right to life would be nullified. In retort, the court took the view that the right to life argument was inappropriate as the Constitution had express provisions governing issues of access to health-care services. In adopting this approach, the court unduly minimised the rel- evance of section 11. Even conceding that chronic renal failure of the type that the appellant was afflicted with did not constitute a medical emergency as contemplated by section 27(3), the effect of the court’s interpretation was to cast the provisions of the Bill of Rights as individual elements that are not linked. The court thus adopted a legalistic interpretation of section 27(3) in contrast with its own professed generous, purposive approach.127 It was also a mistake for the court to interpret section 27(3) as a negative rather than a pos- itive right.128 The court held that section 27(3) created a negative right only: the right not to be turned away arbitrarily by an institution or facility that is able to provide emergency treat- ment.129 To the extent that the court’s approach can be construed as imposing no obligation upon the state to develop and make emergency services available, the import of the positive duties of health-care providers was undermined.130 Socio-economic rights draw sustenance 124 Chaskalson P delivered the leading judgment. 125 C Scott & P Alston ‘Adjudicating Constitutional Priorities in a Transnational Context: A Comment on Soobramoney’s Legacy and Grootboom’s Promise’ (2000) 16 SAJHR 207 at 206; De Vos (note 97 above) at 258–259. 126 Soobramoney 1998 (1) SA 765 (CC) par 26. 127 S v Makwanyane 1995 (3) SA 391 (CC) par 9; De Waal, Currie & Erasmus (note 44 above) at 130–135. 128 Soobramoney 1998 (1) SA 765 (CC) par 20. 129 Ibid. 130 Scott & Alston (note 125 above) at 235–237. from the imposition of positive obligations. Scott and Alston have described the court’s approach as constituting ‘negative textual inferentialism’.131 Soobramoney also seems to paint a picture of undue judicial deference in decisions on the allocation of health-care resources and the protection of socio-economic rights in gener- al.132 The court seemed to take as its starting point that once it has been asserted by a provincial or national health-care provider that resources are unavailable, then that per se limits the realisation of a right of access to the service. The court did not inquire into whether the state and the province were in fact according due priority to the realisation of the right sought by making available resources that ought to be available and utilising such resources effectively. It seemed enough for the health-care provider to ‘toll the bell of tight resources’.133 Soobramoney, unlike Treatment Action Campaign, is of little use for understanding the constitutional right to equitable access to health-care services. The court did not consider how the right to health or the right of access to health care has been interpreted under internation- al human rights instruments. In particular, the court failed to make use of jurisprudence that had been developed by the Committee on ESCR. Failure to consider international law was a serious shortcoming on the part of the court, not least because the Constitution enjoins the courts to consider any relevant international law.134 VII Conclusion When viewed from an egalitarian perspective, the South African health-care system had for the greater part of the twentieth century conformed to the paradigm of a lottery where race, income and geographical location have been the main determinants of access. Post- apartheid reforms are, however, challenging this lottery, not least through major health-care reforms and the constitutional imperatives to achieve substantive equality, and perforce equitable access to health-care services. Section 27 of the Constitution is the clearest indi- cation of a commitment towards equity in access to health care. However, political reforms rarely come without contradictions and the same stands true for the reform of the South African health-care system. While the trajectory towards a health-care system that embraces egalitarian equity is clear, there are attendant problems and detracting factors. Providing universal care is cost- ly to a middle-income country that does not have a national health insurance system and has a high unemployment rate.135 South Africa still has poor indicators for health when compared with other middle-income countries.136 The health-care sector is competing with Historical Development of the SA Health-Care System 197 131 Scott & Alston (note 125 above) at 237. 132 D Mollendorf ‘Reasoning about Resources: Soobramoney and the Future of Economic Rights Claims’ (1998) 14 SAJHR 327 at 327. 133 R v Cambridge Health Authority, ex Pb (a minor) (QBD) 25 BMLR 5 17 per Laws J; Soobramoney 1998 (1) SA 765 (CC) par 52 per Sachs J (where drawing from Cambridge Health Authority he said that ‘[i]n a case as the present which engages our compassion to the full, I feel it necessary to underline the fact that Chaskalson P’s judgment, as I understand it, does not “merely toll the bell of lack of resources”’). 134 Sec 39 of the Constitution. 135 M Bachmann ‘Would Social Health Insurance Improve South African Health Care? What other Middle Income Countries Can Teach Us’ (1994) 24 Transformation 26 at 26. 136 Bachmann (note 135 above) at 27. 1 9 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E other sectors for scarce resources. Skilled health workers are emigrating in significant num- bers.137 The burden on the health-care system is increasing on account of rising levels of poverty and unemployment. Perhaps more than any other factor, the gigantic scale of the country’s HIV/AIDS epidemic has been a constraining factor in the realisation of universal access to health care. The divide between a first rate but expensive private health-care sec- tor and a second-class public health sector remains and will persist for the foreseeable future.138 Furthermore, the pace of transformation itself is not above criticism. Changes have at times been introduced well ahead of creating capacity in terms of human resources and other infrastructure.139 Despite these impediments, it is, nonetheless, incontestable that the building blocks for an equitable health-care system are being laid. At least in the medi- um to long term, there is no reason why South Africa cannot realise for all of its people the provision of a decent basic minimum package of care commensurate with resources. While this article has focused on equity in access to health from the angle of policy and prac- tice, it is important to bear in mind that in the case of developing countries the factors that impact on equity are governed not only by internal factors, but also external ones.140 The costs of life-saving or life-prolonging drugs that are manufactured by conglomerates that are based in developed countries are a major constraining factor. The global inequity in access to AIDS drugs is a clear illustration.141 Regardless of the extent of commitment to the provision of anti- retroviral drugs, if the price of drugs is exorbitant and patent protection rules are unduly restrictive and indifferent to public health catastrophes, equity cannot be obtained for the poor in developing countries. 137 ‘Young Doctors Plan to Bolt en Masse’ Sunday Times 2002-12-08. A survey carried out on new medical graduates has revealed that 43% intend to leave the country and that only 38% are committed to working in the public health sector. 138 Van Rensburg (note 87 above) at 1. 139 Ibid. 140 HCJ Van Rensburg & C Ngwena ‘Health and Health Care in South Africa against an African Background’ in WC Cockerham (ed) The Blackwell Companion to Medical Sociology (2001) at 365–391. 141 CA Reich ‘The Global Drug Gap’ (2000) 287 Science 1979 at 1979; D Resnik ‘Developing Drugs for the Developing World: An Economic, Legal, Moral and Political Dilemma’ (2001) 1 Developing World Bioethics 11 at 11. Pro-Poor Court, Anti-Poor Outcomes: Explaining The Performance of the South African Land Claims Court T H E U N I S R O U X * Director, South African Institute for Advanced Constitutional, Public, Human Rights and International Law; Honorary Reader in Law, University of the Witwatersrand I Introduction Why has a specialist court that was purposely established to adjudicate claims made under pro- poor legislation come to play a very minor role in the adjudication of those claims? How did it happen that a decision of that court rejecting a claim by an indigenous community should be overturned by an appellate court staffed by non-specialist judges? And why did the specialist court, in several decisions across different areas of law, interpret social rights so narrowly that they were rendered virtually meaningless? These are some of the questions that have driven the writing of this article. The court in ques- tion, the Land Claims Court of South Africa (‘the LCC’), was established in 1996 under a statute that was among the first wave of legislation enacted by the post-apartheid legislature. Indeed, the statute concerned, the Restitution of Land Rights Act,1 was so important to the new democratic government that special authorisation for it was built into the transitional constitution.2 Anyone reading the Restitution Act at the time of its promulgation would have had no doubt that the LCC had been established to oversee the reversal of eighty years of state-orchestrated land dispossession. And anyone observing the process of its establishment would have noted that the judges chosen to staff the Court all had strong human rights credentials. None of them had served as a judge under apartheid,3 and all had in their previous work as practising lawyers demonstrated their commit- ment to improving the lives of the poor and the landless. And yet, ten years later, the LCC plays no * I would like to thank the anonymous referees of this article for their helpful comments, and also the par- ticipants in the two conferences at which draft versions of this article were presented: the Centre for Applied Legal Studies conference on Human Rights, Democracy and Social Transformation: When do Rights Work? (November 2003), and the University of the Witwatersrand Law School conference celebrating Twenty Years of Human Rights Scholarship and Ten Years of Democracy (July 2004). This article first appeared in (2004) 20 SAJHR 511-543 and is reprinted here with the kind permission of T Roux, I Currie (editor of SAJHR) and Juta & Co. 1 Act 22 of 1994 (‘the Restitution Act’). 2 See sections 121-123 of the Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, Act 200 of 1993. 3 As noted below, the President of the court, Fikile Bam, had acted as an additional member of the Industrial Courts in the former Ciskei and Transkei ‘homelands’, after being deported from South Africa in 1980. 2 0 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E meaningful role in overseeing the land restitution process, and has concurrent jurisdiction over another statute that, at least in part because of the way the Court has interpreted it, is regarded as ‘facilitating’ a new wave of land dispossession.4 In seeking to explain this anomaly, this article draws on the work of a group of scholars who are studying the role of courts in new democracies. The group is particularly interested in two issues: the accountability function of courts (which concerns the capacity of courts to check the power of the political branches), and the role of courts in social transformation. The first phase of this study has been completed.5 The second phase, to which this article belongs, tests a the- oretical model of the role of courts in social transformation that is described in detail else- where.6 In brief, the model assumes that the capacity of courts to be used as agents for social transformation is influenced by a number of ‘indicators’, including: institutional indicators (such as the structure of the legal system and the social composition of the judiciary), indica- tors of poor groups’ voice (the frequency and nature of cases brought), and resource indicators and indicators of access to justice barriers (such as access to legal aid and other funding for lit- igation, and motivational, psychological and practical barriers to access).7 What makes the study of the LCC interesting for purposes of this model is that it provides an opportunity to eliminate some of the variables that typically condition the social transfor- mation performance of courts, such as the social composition of the judiciary and the underly- ing legal framework. Neither of these factors can explain the performance of the LCC in the areas of law just described. The judges on the court, one may safely assume, have not changed their political opinions since their appointment, and the legislation that the LCC is required to enforce remains stridently pro-poor. If the theoretical model tested in this article is sound, this means that the performance of the LCC in these areas must be explicable in terms of one or more of the remaining indicators: either a resource indicator (such as the absence of legal aid or lawyers capable of pursuing effective, pro-poor legal strategies), an access to justice barrier (such as the physical location of the court, the inaccessibility of the legal language used to artic- ulate the claims of the poor, and various other motivational and psychological barriers to access), or an institutional indicator (such as the influence of legal culture, the doctrinal force of the common law, or professional concerns amongst the judges about how their decisions are perceived). Before examining the possible role of these indicators it is necessary first to describe in more detail the nature and functions of the LCC, including the social background of the judges who staff it, the history of its establishment, and the character of the legislation it administers. In addition to reinforcing the points made already in relation to the history of the Court, this sec- 4 The term ‘facilitating’ was used by several speakers at the ESTA Review Workshop held in November 1999 to describe the impact of the Extension of Security of Tenure Act 62 of 1997 (‘the ESTA’) on farm workers. See Department of Land Affairs: Land Rights Directorate ESTA Review Workshop Report (December 1999). At this workshop, which was attended by a wide cross-section of government officials, NGO work- ers and representatives of the farming community, the ESTA and various judgments of the LCC were severe- ly criticised for failing to stem the tide of farm worker evictions in South Africa. There is at present no empirical evidence to support this claim. 5 See sec Gloppen, R Gargarella & E Skaar (eds) Democratization and the Judiciary: The Accountability Function of Courts in New Democracies (2004) (first published as a special issue of the journal Democratization in 2003). 6 See sec Gloppen ‘Analyzing the Role of Courts in Social Transformation: Social Rights Litigation, Court Responsiveness and Capability’ paper presented at the Centre for Applied Legal Studies Workshop on Human Rights, Democracy and Social Transformation: When do Rights Work? (November 2003). 7 Ibid. tion is intended to make the analysis presented here more accessible to non-South African schol- ars interested in the lessons to be learned from the performance of the LCC. It will also be necessary as a preliminary matter to make out a stronger case for the poor, pro-poor performance of the Court in the areas of law chosen for analysis. Assessments of courts’ performance are inevitably contested, with judges themselves necessarily taking the view, at least when justifying their decisions, that their judgments are doctrinally sound. In addition, other legal academics may take a different view from the one presented here on the doctrinal correctness of the decisions discussed. Since the assessment of the correctness of a legal decision is itself an act of legal interpretation, the argument presented in this article is vul- nerable to the criticism that it is based on a flawed understanding of the record of the Court, particularly since only a fraction of the total number of decisions handed down by the Court will be discussed. The further difficulty is that there is a (very respectable) view in the literature that, given the expense of litigation, every case that goes to court must in theory be capable of decision in favour of either party, and therefore that every act of adjudication is really a deci- sion between plausible legal outcomes.8 Indeed, if the LCC never handed down a decision unfavourable to a poor litigant, this in itself would be anomalous, and of course the landown- ers who litigate the other side of these cases would soon seek another forum in which to defend their interests. This methodological problem is addressed in the following way. After describing the nature and functions of the LCC, the third section of this article discusses a series of cases in four areas of law that produced anti-poor outcomes. By ‘anti-poor outcomes’ is meant cases in which the losing party was poor.9 In relation to cases heard in the LCC the identification of a poor liti- gant is not difficult: the vast majority of the cases decided by the Court involve poor, mostly black claimants asserting or defending their statutory land rights against relatively affluent, mostly white landowners.10 Having classified the cases in this way, the article proceeds to Performance of the SA Land Claims Court 201 8 See F Schauer Playing by the Rules: A Philosophical Examination of Rule-Based Decision-making in Law and in Life (1991) 193 (citing G Priest & W Klein ‘The Selection of Disputes for Litigation’ (1984) 13 J of Legal Studies 1-23) and F Schauer ‘Judging in a Corner of the Law’ (1988) 61 Southern California LR 1717- 33). 9 I draw here on some of the methodology developed in scalogram analysis. In its application by judicial behaviouralists, this form of analysis amounts to distinguishing various judicial attitudes, expressed as antinomies (eg pro-labour/pro-business, pro-regulation/anti-regulation) and then assessing the performance of judges in relation to these antinomies across a number of decisions. See M Shapiro & A Stone Sweet On Law, Politics, and Judicialization (2002) 44-46. Scalogram analysis is generally used to study ordinary courts applying the common law, and in respect of non-unanimous decisions involving issues of public pol- icy decided on the merits. See DE Fouts ‘Policy-Making in the Supreme Court of Canada, 1950-1960’ in G Schubert & DJ Danelski (eds) Comparative Judicial Behavior: Cross-Cultural Studies of Political Decision- Making in the East and West (1969) 257-91, 265. The non-unanimity requirement comes from an assump- tion that the handing down of a dissenting judgment means that there were at least two legally plausible outcomes to the case, and that judicial discretion (in the form of an underlying attitude) therefore came into play. It is this part of the methodology that I draw on here. The full application of scalogram analysis is inappropriate because there has not been a single dissenting judgment in the entire history of the LCC, and the LCC is of course not an ordinary court applying the common law. 10 By using the label ‘anti-poor’ to describe the outcomes in these cases I do not mean to suggest that the Court was motivated by anti-poor sentiments. As will become clearer below, the explanation I posit for these anti- poor outcomes is independent of the judges’ private political views – as indeed it must be, since those views, as far as can be ascertained, are not anti-poor. Rather, I choose the term ‘anti-poor’ because it is the bina- ry opposite of the term ‘pro-poor’, and the anomaly I wish to explore is the anomaly of a pro-poor court, interpreting pro-poor legislation, handing down decisions that adversely affected not just the poor litigants involved, but also other similarly situated poor people. 2 0 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E analyse the written reasons given for the decision in each case. The point of this exercise is not to argue that the cases were wrongly decided, in the sense that the Court made clear mistakes of law. Rather, it is to show that plausible, pro-poor legal arguments were presented to the Court, and then either rejected or ignored. Of course, there is room for doubt at this stage over whether the contention that the reject- ed or ignored arguments were plausible is itself doctrinally sound. In two instances, however, the argument that the cases might have been decided differently is supported by decisions of other courts – one of them the appellate decision mentioned earlier, and the other a minority judgment of a judge of a court of equivalent status to the LCC. By referring to these instances, this article shifts the burden of persuasion onto those who would disagree with its interpreta- tion of the cases to show why these other judgments were so clearly wrong that they were not even plausible. The second way in which this article shores up its arguments relating to plausibility is by referring to independent evidence of the way in which the Court’s decisions were perceived. This evidence comes in the form of responses by the legislature to the LCC’s decisions. In two instances one can draw a direct line of causation between a decision discussed here and an amending statute aimed at counteracting that decision. This does not demonstrate, of course, that the two LCC decisions concerned were not doctrinally sound, or that the pro-poor argu- ments they ignored or rejected were plausible, but it does indicate that the legislature was dis- satisfied with the LCC’s performance. Since the LCC is a creature of statute, this result is sig- nificant enough to warrant investigating. From the perspective of the theoretical model tested in this article, a legislative amendment to social transformation legislation is evidence of poor judicial performance in the weak political sense. The next part of the article considers some possible explanations for the poor, pro-poor per- formance of the LCC in the four areas of law discussed, drawing on, and at the same time test- ing, the theoretical model introduced above. In addition to the two sets of indicators already eliminated, two further explanations will not be pursued in detail here: the absence of legal aid, and the legal strategies pursued by the poor to assert their rights. The absence of legal aid can- not explain anti-poor outcomes in a series of cases across several areas of law where plausible, pro-poor legal arguments were presented to the court.11 The same logic applies to the legal strategies pursued by the poor: to the extent that the LCC was presented with plausible pro- poor legal arguments in the cases discussed here, the anti-poor outcomes cannot be attributed to the legal strategies pursued. This leaves three other possible explanations, all of which have to do with institutional indicators, viz the influence of South African legal culture, the doctrinal force of the common law, and the LCC’s desire for approval from its professional peers. The final part of the arti- cle revisits the cases in an attempt to find an explanation for the anti-poor outcomes in these factors. 11 It could, of course, explain a general tendency of interpreting the rights framework in a way contrary to the poor, but this is a different issue. II Background (A) THE LCC’S JURISDICTION AND COMPETENCE The LCC was established in 1996 and handed down its first decision on 16 April 1996. Since then it has handed down over 300 decisions.12 The LCC’s powers and functions are set out in Chapter III of the Restitution Act. As noted above, the Restitution Act was one of the first statutes to be passed by the post-apartheid legislature, from which one may deduce that the issue of land restitution was given high priority by the incoming government. With hindsight, the Restitution Act was perhaps a little too hastily enacted, as there have been numerous amendments to it, one each year from 1995-2000, and again in 2002. The 1999 amendments were very extensive indeed, and virtually legislated the LCC out of the restitution process. This circumstances giving rise to these amendments are discussed in III (A) below. The LCC’s foundational jurisdiction is derived from section 22 of the Restitution Act. In addi- tion, section 13 of the Land Reform (Labour Tenants) Act (‘the LTA’)13 and section 20 of the Extension of Security of Tenure Act (‘the ESTA’)14 define the LCC’s particular jurisdiction in relation to these statutes. The LCC’s jurisdiction over the Restitution Act and the LTA is exclu- sive of other courts, whereas it shares jurisdiction over the ESTA with the magistrates’ courts and the High Court. In practice, the LCC hands down very few decisions under the Restitution Act (about seven a year),15 and the overwhelming majority of restitution claims are settled in terms of the powers conferred on the Minister of Land Affairs under section 42D of the Restitution Act (as amended in 1999).16 The LCC also decides very few labour tenants cases (about five a year),17 notwithstanding the provision in section 13 of the LTA that all labour tenants matters in other courts be referred to the LCC, except where oral evidence has already been led. The vast majority of the LCC’s work, as a proportion of judgments delivered, involves its automatic review jurisdiction under section 19(3) of the ESTA. Over 50 per cent of the LCC’s total output since 1998 has consisted of decisions of this type.18 The LCC’s automatic review jurisdiction has been described as a hybrid jurisdiction, combining elements of appeal and review.19 In essence, on every occasion in which a magistrate hands down an order for eviction against a person who qualifies as a protected occupier under the ESTA, the decision must be sent on review to the LCC. In an important line of cases, the LCC has extended its jurisdiction in this context to all magistrates’ court orders for eviction falling into the ‘sphere of law’ defined by the ESTA.20 Thus, even where the eviction order is not technically speaking handed down Performance of the SA Land Claims Court 203 12 As at the end of June 2004. 13 Act 3 of 1996. 14 Act 62 of 1997. 15 My list contains 53 decisions between 1996 and July 2003, including decisions in applications for leave to appeal. 16 The latest figure available from the Commission on Restitution of Land Rights is that 36 908 restitution claims had been settled by 28 February 2003. 17 My list contains 38 decisions between 1996 and July 2003, including decisions in applications for leave to appeal. 18 The respective percentages for each year of operation of the ESTA are: 1998 (28.8%), 1999 (51.5%), 2000 (72%), 2001 (68.5%), 2002 (59.4%), 2003 (40.7%), 2004 to date (61.5%). 19 Lategan v Koopman en Andere 1998 (3) SA 457 (LCC) at 464C, Atkinson v Van Wyk and Another 1999 (1) SA 1080 (LCC) at 1085-86. 20 See Skhosana and Others v Roos t/a Roos se Oord and Others 2000 (4) SA 561 (LCC), Pitout v Mbolane [2000] 2 All SA 377 (LCC), Mahlangu and another v Van Eeden and another [2000] 3 All SA 321 (LCC), Bergboerdery v Makgoro 2000 (4) SA 575 (LCC), Khuzwayo v Dludla [2000] 4 All SA 329 (LCC), and Van Zyl NO v Maarman [2000] 4 All SA 212 (LCC). 2 0 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E in terms of the ESTA, the LCC will assume jurisdiction to review it if the ESTA was raised in argument, or should have been applied as a matter of law. In a further important decision handed down in 2001, however, the LCC held that its auto- matic review decisions, being decisions of a single judge sitting in chambers, were not formal deci- sions as such.21 Accordingly, in the event of an appeal being raised against such a decision, the appeal should lie first to a two-judge bench of the LCC, and then to the Supreme Court of Appeal. This means that just more than half of the LCC’s decisions are not really decisions at all. The remainder of the LCC’s workload consists of cases under the ESTA that are initiated in the LCC itself. These cases mainly take the form of urgent applications for eviction and appli- cations to enforce occupiers’ or owners’ use rights. The magistrates’ court rules in South Africa are not designed to deal with urgent applications, and hence these cases go directly to the LCC. (B) THE SOCIAL COMPOSITION OF THE COURT There are now four LCC judges: two African men, one Indian woman, and one white man. A fifth judge, a white man, resigned from the Court in 2000 to pursue a career as an advocate at the Johannesburg Bar. The four sitting judges all have backgrounds in human rights law.22 The Judge President, Fikile Bam, was a former Director of the Legal Resources Centre in Port Elizabeth, and sat on the Goldstone Commission of Inquiry. Judge Antonie Gildenhuys, although a former member of the secret Afrikaner club, the Broederbond, went through a self-described personal political transformation in the early 1990s as chair of the National Peace Secretariat. Judge Gildenhuys is also a former President of the Transvaal Law Society, and the author of a leading academic textbook on the law of expropriation. Judge Yasmin Meer’s human rights background includes a brief stint, in 1995, as National Director of South Africa’s leading public interest litigation firm, the Legal Resources Centre. Before that, she practised as an attorney at the Legal Resources Centre for 12 years. Judge Justice Moloto (‘Justice’ is his first name), although never a human rights lawyer, was executive director of the Black Lawyers’ Legal Education Centre for five years, and has been committed throughout his professional career to the development of young black lawyers. (C) LEGAL EDUCATION AND TRAINING OF JUDGES All of the LCC judges have had a formal university legal education. During the period when the judges were in training, university education in South Africa was, with a few exceptions, seg- regated on racial lines, and black lawyers were thus trained either at an historically black uni- versity (like the University of Durban-Westville, where Judge Meer obtained her BA degree) or at a distance learning university, like the University of South Africa (Judges Bam and Moloto). Judge Meer later attended the University of Cape Town for her LLB degree, and the University of Warwick (LLM). Very unusually for his time, President Bam’s first law degree, a BA (Law), was from the University of Cape Town. Judge Gildenhuys graduated BA LLB from the University of Pretoria. He also has a LLD from the University of South Africa. Three of the four judges practised as attorneys before being appointed to the LCC, Judge 21 See Magodi and others v Van Rensburg [2001] 4 All SA 485 (LCC). 22 The information in this section and the next one is taken from the LCC’s website . Meer at the LRC, Judge Gildenhuys in a commercial law firm in Johannesburg, and Judge Moloto as an attorney in Durban. The only former advocate amongst the judges is Judge President Bam, who was a member of the Johannesburg Bar and then the Transkei Bar, after being deported from South Africa in 1980. Judge President Bam is also the only one of the four to have had previous judicial experience, as an additional member of the Industrial Courts in the former Ciskei and Transkei ‘homelands’. (D) JUDGES’ PERCEPTION OF THEIR ROLE In its early judgments the LCC expressly stated that it saw itself as interpreting and applying ‘social legislation’, by which it meant legislation whose primary objective was to transform social power structures in favour of the landless groups identified in that legislation. This approach came out most strongly in its judgments on costs orders, where it developed the prin- ciple that costs should generally not be awarded against a poor litigant who litigates in good faith on a novel point of law. Thus the LCC has held that punitive, attorney-client costs will only be awarded where one party litigates ‘maliciously or in wilful disregard of the [other party’s] rights’,23 that ‘[i]t is not always appropriate to grant [ordinary] costs orders in respect of litigation under [the ESTA]’,24 and that parties should not be discouraged from enforcing their rights under social legislation by the fear of an adverse costs order.25 The principle that costs should generally not be awarded against a litigant who has litigated in good faith is direct- ly opposed to the common-law principle that ‘costs follow the result’, ie that the losing party should pay the other side’s costs, whatever their personal economic circumstances might be. The mere fact that the judges of the LCC perceive themselves to be interpreting social legis- lation does not, of course, mean that their judgments have the effect of promoting the objec- tives of that legislation. As argued below, it may be that in practice other factors, such as the legal culture in which they are operating, their greater familiarity with the common law, and their desire for professional respect, exert a restraining influence on their choice of legal rules. Only a close reading of the cases will reveal the extent of the rule choices open to them, and the possible influences on the exercise of their discretion in areas of legal uncertainty – to which task this article now turns. III The Cases The four areas of law chosen for analysis in this article are: (a) the confirmation of out-of-court settlement agreements made in terms of the Restitution Act; (b) the validity of a claim made by an indigenous community under the Restitution Act to return of its ancestral land; (c) the enforce- ment of rural farm dwellers’ right under the Extension of Security of Tenure Act 62 of 1997 (‘the ESTA’) to bury their relatives on the land on which they are residing; and (d) dependants and spouses’ rights under the ESTA not to be arbitrarily evicted. As explained above, these areas were all chosen because they illustrate instances in which the LCC decided cases against poor litigants, Performance of the SA Land Claims Court 205 23 Karabo and Others v Kok and Others 1998 (1) SA 1014 (LCC) at 1024I. 24 Serole and Another v Pienaar 2000 (1) SA 328 (LCC) at 336E. 25 Skhosana v Roos [1999] 2 All SA 652 (LCC) at 666c-e. See also the LCC’s decisions on costs orders under the LTA: Hlatshwayo v Hein 1999 (2) SA 834 (LCC) at 844-50 and Mahlangu v De Jager 1996 (3) SA 325 (LCC) at 246F-247D. 2 0 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E despite the existence of plausible legal arguments justifying an alternative outcome. The cases dis- cussed represent only a fraction of the total number of cases decided by the LCC, most of which have had pro-poor outcomes. The discussion that follows therefore does not purport to be an assessment of the overall performance of the LCC, which would require a book-length study. Rather, my intention is to focus on a set of apparently anomalous outcomes in the hope that the explantory power of the model tested in this article can be demonstrated. (A) SUPERVISION OF RESTITUTION SETTLEMENTS In its very first decision under the Restitution Act, In re Macleantown Residents Association: Re Certain Erven and Commonage in Macleantown (‘the Macleantown case’),26 the LCC was required to endorse a settlement agreement that had been reached between an urban land- claiming community, a local ratepayers’ association, and a municipality. The agreement had been signed after painstaking negotiations, and was described by the LCC in its judgment as demonstrating ‘a common-sense approach to the restitution claim’.27 Nevertheless, the LCC refused to endorse it. The main reasons given for this decision were: ‘the papers submitted to the Court [did] not contain a list of [individual] claimants’,28 no resolutions were filed autho- rising the representatives of the land-claiming community and the ratepayers’ association to sign the settlement agreement on behalf of their constituents,29 there was no proof that the local government authority had the legal power to transfer the land in question to the land-claiming community,30 the ‘involvement’ of each individual member of the land-claiming community in the original land dispossession had not been made out on the papers,31 and the proper Deeds Office description of the land claimed had not been submitted to court.32 Although all of these requirements were technically speaking necessary for the Court to make an effective order, the Restitution Act did not expressly confer on the Court the power to refuse to endorse a settlement agreement for non-compliance with these requirements. Rather, the Court arrives at this rule through interpreting section 14(3) of the Act.33 Section 14(3), as it was then formulated,34 simply set out the procedure that the Commission on Restitution of Land Rights had to follow in referring settlement agreements to the Court. Section 14(6), to which the Court refers in a footnote,35 then went on to provide that the Court should not make an order ‘unless the Commission has, in respect of the claim in question, acted in accordance with the provisions of this section’.36 This provision plainly referred to compliance by the Commission with the procedural steps required by section 14, rather than the substantive requirements for a valid restitution claim. And yet, it is the latter interpretation that the Court prefers, glossing section 14(6) as meaning that, before making a settlement agreement an order 26 1996 (4) SA 1272 (LCC). 27 Ibid 1275C. 28 Ibid 1278B. 29 Ibid 1279D. 30 Ibid 1279F. 31 Ibid 1280E. 32 Ibid 1281E. 33 Ibid 1276G-I. 34 This subsection has since been substituted by sec 6(b) of the Land Restitution and Reform Laws Amendment Act 18 of 1999. 35 Macleantown (note 26 above) 1276J. 36 This subsection has also since been amended, by sec 10(1)(b) of the Land Restitution and Reform Laws Amendment Act and sec 6(e) of the Land Restitution and Reform Laws Amendment Act 18 of 1999. of court, it must ‘determine whether all requirements imposed by such legislation [ie the Restitution Act] have been met’.37 Not surprisingly, the Macleantown decision was very badly received by the Commission, which seems to have understood it as a criticism of its technical competence. At the time, the Commission was struggling under the massive weight of the unexpectedly large number of resti- tution claims lodged, which were then reckoned at 64 000.38 Of these, the Commission had set- tled only one by the end of the fiscal year in which the Macleantown case was decided.39 By insisting on detailed technical compliance with the Act in an uncontested case where all the par- ties were in favour of the solution reached, the LCC missed a crucial opportunity to set itself up as a partner to the Commission in pursuit of the overall policy objectives of the Act. That the decision in the Macleantown case was not dictated by the Restitution Act is illus- trated by a decision of the LCC handed down some three months later, In re Elandskloof Vereniging.40 In this case, the LCC held that its role in relation to the supervision of settlement agreements was not, after all, to assess the underlying validity of the restitution claim, provid- ed the settlement agreement was fairly reached.41 This holding directly contradicted the dictum in Macleantown that ‘[t]he Court can only make a settlement agreement an order of Court if it is a competent order of the Court in terms of the Act’.42 Although the meaning of this dictum is not entirely clear in the abstract, the Court in the very next paragraph of the Macleantown judgment proceeded to inquire whether the claimants had been ‘dispossessed after 1913 under racially discriminatory legislation’,43 confirming that it thought that it was under a duty to ensure that the claim was a valid one under the Restitution Act. This aspect of the holding in Macleantown is quietly abandoned in the Elandskloof case, which does not refer to the Macleantown decision, despite the fact that it was directly in point. Within a year and a half of the Macleantown decision, a new section 42D had been inserted in the Restitution Act giving the Minister of Land Affairs the power to endorse settlement agreements in consultation with the Commission on Restitution of Land Rights, to the exclu- sion of the Court.44 It is impossible to determine the role played by the Macleantown decision in this amendment. But the consequence of the amendment is clear: today, only a minute frac- tion of the total number of restitution claims are decided by the LCC, the vast majority being settled through the administrative procedure laid down in section 42D. The LCC, which was originally conceived as the main institution through which restitution claims would be adjudi- cated, has been virtually legislated out of the restitution process. Performance of the SA Land Claims Court 207 37 Macleantown (note 26 above) 1276H. 38 The total number of restitution claims lodged changes as the investigation of the claims by the Commission pro- ceeds, mainly because some claims are split on investigation into two or more claims. As at the end of December 1998, the total number of claims stood at 63 455, but this has since escalated to 72 975. See R Hall ‘Rural Land Restitution in South Africa’ paper prepared for Programme for Land and Agrarian Studies (July 2003) at 25. 39 Ibid 26. 40 1999 (1) SA 176 (LCC). 41 Ibid 179E. 42 Macleantown (note 26 above) at 1276I-J. 43 Ibid 1277A-F. 44 Inserted by sec 30 of the Land Restitution and Reform Laws Amendment Act 63 of 1997, which came into effect on 21 November 1997. (The Macleantown decision was ahnded down on 4 July 1996.) Section 42D was later substituted by sec 12 of the Land Restitution and Reform Laws Amendment Act 18 of 1999. The substituted provision, which was enacted after a comprehensive ministerial review of the restitution process, including interviews with the LCC and the Commission, goes even further in empowering the Minister to enter into settlement agreements with parties interested in a claim. 2 0 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E (B) CLAIMS BASED ON THE DOCTRINE OF ABORIGINAL TITLE UNDER THE RESTITUTION ACT The question whether the doctrine of aboriginal title, which has been used by indigenous groups in Australia and Canada to claim back their ancestral land, might be applicable in South Africa has loomed large over the restitution process for some time.45 Given the scale of land dispossession, and the proportion of the population that would be able to show a continuing connection to an indigenous group, the adoption of this doctrine would have a significant impact on the stability of land titles across the country. In recognition of this, the African National Congress, during the constitutional negotiations leading up to the adoption of the 1993 South African Constitution, agreed to set 19 June 1913 as the cut-off date for the statu- tory land restitution process.46 The effect of this agreement was to prohibit claims for restitu- tion from people or communities who had been dispossessed of a right in land before this date. The cut-off date did not, however, exclude such claims from being brought under the common law, or indeed claims under the Restitution Act in which the claimants alleged that they had been dispossessed of their aboriginal rights after 19 June 1913. The first, and thus far only, claim of this kind brought in South Africa involved a communi- ty of Khoi San people whose ancestral land is situated in the northwestern corner of South Africa, just south of the Namibian border, stretching all the way to the Atlantic Ocean. The coastal portion of the land is the site of rich alluvial diamond deposits, which have for a long time been mined by a state-owned mining company, Alexkor Ltd. The claimant group, known collectively as the Richtersveld Community, launched two separate cases claiming return of this land. The first case, in the Cape High Court, was based squarely on the doctrine of aboriginal title, which the Richtersveld Community alleged was part of South African common law. The second case, under the Restitution Act, was launched in the LCC. In its first decision in this case, the LCC dismissed a special plea of lis pendens by Alexkor Ltd, holding that the Richterveld Community’s cause of action in the High Court case was suf- ficiently different from the case launched in the LCC to warrant continuing with the latter.47 In its decision on the main issue,48 however, the LCC ruled against the claimant community. According to the first principle of intertemporal law, the Court held, the consequences of the colonial acquisition of a territory must be examined on the basis of the conditions and rules in existence at the time of colonisation.49 It was clear from the surrounding documents that, upon annexation in 1847, the British colonial government assumed full ownership of the Richtersveld, to the exclusion of the Richtersveld Community. The community accordingly had no ownership rights in the subject land after 1913.50 To the extent that their claim was based not on ownership but on aboriginal title, the LCC did not have jurisdiction to decide it because the recognition of aboriginal title depended on the development of the common law.51 Whilst 45 See T Bennett & C Powell ‘Aboriginal Title in South Africa Revisted’ (1999) 15 SAJHR at 449. 46 See Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, Act 200 of 1993. This date is repeated in sec 25(7) of the 1996 Constitution, and in sec 2 of the Restitution Act. Its significance derives from the fact that it was the day on which the Natives Land Act 28 of 1913 commenced. 47 Richtersveld Community v Alexkor Ltd and another 2000 (1) SA 337 (LCC). 48 Richtersveld Community and others v Alexkor Ltd and another 2001 (3) SA 1293 (LCC). 49 Ibid para 42. 50 Ibid para 43. 51 Ibid para 47. it was possible that an aboriginal title right could be recognised as a ‘customary law interest’ for purposes of the Restitution Act, the Court held, such a step again depended on the devel- opment of the common law, and thus fell outside the LCC’s jurisdiction.52 The only basis, therefore, on which the Richtersveld Community could be said to have enjoyed rights in land over the Richtersveld was as beneficial occupiers.53 To succeed in their claim, the Richtersveld Community had to prove that they had been dispossessed of such rights after 1913 as a result of ‘past racially discriminatory laws or practices’. According to the LCC’s previous decisions on this point, this meant that they had to prove dispossession in terms of ‘a law or practice designed to bring about spatial apartheid’.54 None of the laws that had been used to dispossess the Richtersveld Community were of this type, the Court held, being mostly mining laws that were only indirectly discriminatory.55 Nor were any of the practices followed in dispossessing the Richtersveld Community of their land deliberately racist. Rather, they were race-neutral practices aimed at securing the land for mining purposes.56 The LCC accordingly dismissed the claim with a recommendation that the Minister of Land Affairs should consider granting the plaintiffs alternative relief in terms of section 38E(d) of the Restitution Act.57 The LCC was soon asked to revisit its decision in the form of an application for leave to appeal to the Constitutional Court, alternatively the Supreme Court of Appeal. In accordance with the somewhat curious practice that prevails in South Africa, this required the LCC to decide whether there was a reasonable prospect that the Constitutional Court or the Supreme Court of Appeal would come to a different conclusion, which was a bit like asking it to decide whether there was any possibility that it might have been wrong. In the event, the LCC refused leave to appeal for much the same reasons given in its main judgment.58 The Richtersveld Community’s direct appli- cation to the Supreme Court of Appeal was, however, subsequently granted. The confidence demonstrated by the LCC in refusing leave to appeal was not borne out by the Supreme Court of Appeal’s judgment, which emphatically rejected the two main bases for the LCC’s decision.59 The first point of difference concerned the effect of the annexation of the Richtersveld by the Cape Colony in 1847. On this point, the LCC had held that, since the colo- nial authorities had not expressly recognised the existing rights of the Richtersveld people, the effect of the annexation was to extinguish them. On the contrary, the Supreme Court of Appeal held, ‘a mere change in sovereignty does not extinguish the private property rights of the inhab- itants of a conquered territory which continue in force unless confiscated by an act of state’.60 In any event, on the facts, it was not clear whether the colonial authorities had not recognised the rights of the Richtersveld people.61 In relation to the issue of whether the Richtersveld Community had been dispossessed of their rights ‘as a result of past racially discriminatory laws or practices’, the Supreme Court of Performance of the SA Land Claims Court 209 52 Ibid para 53. 53 Ibid para 65. A beneficial occupier under the Restitution Act is someone who has been in occupation of the land for ‘not less than 10 years prior to the dispossession in question’ (see definition of ‘right in land’ in sec 1). 54 Ibid para 93, citing Minister of Land Affairs and Another v Slamdien and others [1999] 1 All SA 608 (LCC); 1999 (4) BCLR 413 (LCC). 55 Ibid para 98. 56 Ibid para 113. 57 Ibid para 118. 58 Richtersveld and others v Alexkor Ltd and another [2001] 4 All SA 563 (LCC) paras 13-26. 59 Richtersveld Community and others v Alexkor Ltd and another [2003] 2 All SA 27 (SCA). 60 Ibid para 55. 61 Ibid para 62. 2 1 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E Appeal again emphatically rejected the LCC’s reasoning. In particular, the Supreme Court of Appeal held that the LCC’s interpretation of this phrase as meaning that the law or practice concerned had to relate to the furtherance of ‘spatial apartheid’ was too ‘restrictive’.62 ‘The real ratio of the judgment in Slamdien was … not the absence of “spatial apartheid” measures but that the [Restitution] Act limited restitution remedies to people who had been discriminated against in the exercise of their land rights’.63 It was clear from the evidence that, although there may have been no intention on the part of the state to discriminate against the Richtersveld Community, the effect of the laws and practices applied to them had been discriminatory.64 In accordance with the Constitutional Court’s equality jurisprudence, this was all that the claimant community had to show.65 The significance of the Supreme Court of Appeal’s reversal of the LCC’s decision in the Richtersveld case is that it is based on two principles of law that a specialised court might have been expected to have got right. The LCC’s ‘doctrine of recognition’ approach to the effect of the annexation of the Richtersveld has been widely discredited in foreign law and was not in any event borne out by the evidence. Similarly, the LCC’s failure to emphasise the obviously dis- criminatory impact of the laws and practices at issue in this case is very puzzling. The passages on this point in the LCC judgment read like a wilful denial of the obvious. At the very least, the Supreme Court of Appeal’s decision confirms that there were plausible legal arguments jus- tifying a pro-poor outcome to the case, and that these were ignored. Why should this have hap- pened? The answer clearly does not lie in the absence of legal aid or in the legal strategy pur- sued by the Richtersveld Community, since the Legal Resources Centre supported the Com- munity throughout, with the assistance of one of South Africa’s leading advocates.66 The answer must lie somewhere else, in one or more of the institutional indicators impacting on the LCC’s performance. The next section explores this question further. Before doing so, two addi- tional areas of law in which the LCC has ignored or rejected plausible pro-poor arguments are discussed, this time involving the interpretation of the Extension of Security of Tenure Act, a tenancy protection statute over which the LCC was given jurisdiction in 1997. (C) RIGHTS OF SPOUSES AND DEPENDANTS AGAINST ARBITRARY EVICTION According to the semi-feudal arrangements that still prevail on many South African farms, the primary employment relationship is that between the farmer and the male ‘head’ of the farm worker household, with the household head’s spouse and other dependants deriving their right to reside on the farm through him. Often, this belies an actual situation where the spouse is also employed on the farm, with her own separate contractual relationship with the landowner. Under the common law, and according to conventional pleading practice, the de facto existence of two separate contractual relationships is ignored, and a plaintiff may institute an action for ejectment against the male head of household, citing the spouse and dependants as ‘all those who derive their right to occupy the property through him’. In the draft version of the Extension of Security of Tenure Act (‘ESTA’) that was published for public comment in February 1997, an express distinction was made between ‘primary’ and 62 Ibid para 97. 63 Ibid para 99. 64 Ibid para 104. 65 Ibid para 105. The Supreme Court of Appeal’s decision was confirmed on appeal to the Constitutional Court. See Alexkor Ltd and Another v Richtersveld Community and Others 2004 (5) SA 460 (CC). 66 Wim Trengove SC. ‘secondary’ occupiers, the latter category consisting mainly of women and children living on commercial farms. The clear intention behind this distinction was to amend the common law by providing special protection against arbitrary eviction to the latter group. After an inter- vention by the National Land Committee,67 however, the drafters were persuaded that the dis- tinction between primary and secondary occupiers would only perpetuate the discriminatory treatment of female farm workers. The distinction was accordingly dropped. Secondary occu- piers, the drafters assured everyone, would be protected as occupiers in their own right. In its decision in Conradie v Hanekom and Another,68 the LCC appeared to vindicate this bold step when ruling that a woman, whose husband had been dismissed for assaulting a fel- low farm worker, could not be evicted merely for that reason. Since she was herself an employ- ee on the farm, and therefore an occupier in her own right, the LCC held, separate grounds for evicting her had to be alleged and proven.69 Not only that, but her husband, although lawful- ly dismissed and therefore liable to eviction under the Act, could not be denied access to the farm, because his wife’s right to family life entitled her to have him stay with her.70 In effect, this meant that he could not be evicted either. The Conradie judgment was immediately hailed as a triumph for court-driven social transfor- mation in South Africa, overturning as it did the centuries-old vulnerability of female farm work- ers to the consequences of their husbands’ actions. Unfortunately, the victory was short-lived: some two and a half years later, in Die Landbou Navorsingsraaad v Klaasen,71 a different judge of the LCC glossed and restricted the Conradie judgment. The Klaasen gloss effectively re-instates the discarded distinction between primary and secondary occupiers, but without restoring the spe- cial protection originally provided for the latter group. According to the LCC in this case, the ‘gen- eral rule’ in eviction proceedings in South Africa is that ‘the sheriff may remove from the farm any person claiming [a right of occupation] through or under [an] occupier’.72 The ESTA did not expressly change this rule. On the contrary, it appeared to support it in a number of provisions that implied that ‘an eviction order against an “occupier” (as defined) is also operative against family members living with that occupier’.73 In addition, the term occupier in the ESTA was used inconsistently, resulting in several ‘incongruities’, including the situation at issue in the Conradie case, where a lawfully dismissed farm worker was allowed to remain on the farm on the basis of his wife’s right to family life.74 It followed that the word ‘occupier’ had to be understood in a wide and a narrow sense. Occupiers in the wide sense fell ‘outside the statutory definition of “occupi- er”’ and accordingly did not enjoy protection in their own right.75 This interpretation, the Court added, would not ‘disempower’ such occupiers because their needs were given special attention in the Act, and they would in the end enjoy the same protection against eviction as the occupier from whom they derived their right to reside on the land.76 Performance of the SA Land Claims Court 211 67 One of the main non-governmental organisations active in the land sector in South Africa. 68 1999 (4) SA 491 (LCC). 69 Ibid para 20. 70 Ibid para 21(vii), citing sec 6(2)(d) of ESTA. 71 LCC Case 83R/01 (unreported judgment of Gildenhuys AJ handed down on 29 October 2001) para 24. 72 Ibid para 26, citing Ntai and others v Vereniging Town Council and Another 1953 (4) SA 579 (A) at 584 and 590. 73 Ibid para 26 (citing two examples in paras 27 and 28). 74 Ibid para 32. 75 Ibid para 33. 76 Ibid para 34. 2 1 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E Whereas the effect of the Conradie judgment had been to force landowners, when drafting pleadings in an action for ejectment under the ESTA, to cite each member of the male farm worker’s family by name, and allege separate substantive grounds for their eviction (which might have included an express allegation that their permission to reside on the property was entirely derived through the male farm worker), the practical effect of the Klaasen judgment has been to restore the common-law position in so far as the method of citation of a farm worker’s spouse and dependants is concerned. In the result, female farm workers and their children are once again being routinely evicted along with their husbands, unless they can prove (the bur- den being on them) that their tenure rights are not derivative on the tenure rights of the male head of household (because, for example, their employment contract states or implies that they have a right to reside on the farm notwithstanding the dismissal of their husband) . (D) FARM DWELLERS’ BURIAL RIGHTS UNDER THE ESTA The LCC’s somewhat reluctant embrace of the transformative potential of the ESTA is further discernible in its approach to occupiers’ right to bury relatives on land belonging to someone else. In South African law, the right to bury a relative is a sui generis right, but comes closest to a personal servitude in favour of the deceased’s relatives, in perpetuity.77 At common law, per- sonal servitudes are typically created by agreement between the owner of the servient tenement and the servitude holder. The servitude binds successors in title of the servient tenement if reg- istered, provided it satisfies the so-called ‘subtraction from dominium’ test.78 As originally enacted, section 6 of the ESTA conferred certain use and service rights on stau- torily protected occupiers, but did not specifically confer on them the right to bury their rela- tives on the land on which they were staying. Rather, section 6(4) conferred on everyone (whether or not they qualified as an occupier) the right to visit and maintain family graves, sub- ject to reasonable conditions imposed by the owner or person in charge of the land. The ESTA also conferred on occupiers the right to ‘freedom of religion, belief and opinion and of expres- sion’,79 and the right ‘to family life in accordance with the culture of that family’.80 For many rural African families in South Africa, the right to culture protects a sphere of personal life that is indistinguishable from that protected by the freedom of religion, and includes the important cultural practice of communicating with their ancestors through the establishment, ritual visit- ing, and maintenance of family burial sites. In Serole and Another v Pienaar,81 the LCC was asked to enforce an alleged right to bury the applicant’s family member, either as a use right under the ESTA, or in terms of the applicant’s rights, as a protected occupier, to culture. Comparing the granting of permission to establish a grave to the granting of a servitude, and therefore ‘a significant inroad into the owner’s common-law property rights’82 the LCC dismissed the application. Before enforcing a right to bury a relative on land belonging to someone else, the LCC held, the Court would need to be convinced by suitable evidence 77 It is not a personal servitude in the strict sense, because a personal servitude is typically granted in favour of a single person for their lifetime. In the case of burial rights, the servitude is effectively granted in favour of a family, including descendants yet to be born. 78 Laid down in Ex parte Geldenhuys 1926 OPD 155. 79 Sec 5(e). 80 Sec 6(2)(d). 81 2000 (1) SA 328 (LCC). 82 Ibid para 16. that occupiers had an express or tacit contractual right to this effect.83 Mere evidence of the exis- tence of a graveyard that had been used in the past would not suffice.84 The Serole decision was cited with approval in Buhrmann v Nkosi and another,85 a Full Bench decision of the Transvaal Provincial Division, which was was later confirmed on appeal.86 Although the reasons for decision given in the two main Buhrmann judgments differ somewhat from the reasons given in the LCC judgment, the three courts adopt essentially the same view, viz that in a direct conflict between the right to property and the right to culture and religion, the former must trump the latter. The only dissenting voice in Buhrmann was that of Ngoepe JP, who wrote a minority judgment in the Full Bench decision in which he argued that a landowner’s property right in a small piece of earth could not be said to trump a sincerely held religious belief.87 It is perhaps not insignificant that Ngoepe JP was the only African judge involved in deciding the Buhrmann case. Certainly, his judgment, in quoting a lengthy passage from the occupier’s affidavit,88 reveals an understanding of the importance of the practice of ancestor worship that is absent from the other judgments. Not only is his judgment more understanding of this practice, but it also presents a plausible legal argument that might have justified an alternative outcome, not only in the Buhrmann case, but also in Serole. In essence, Ngoepe JP argues, the dispute over occupiers’ burial rights under the ESTA represents an irres- oluble conflict between the interests of owners and occupiers, each of whom can claim protec- tion for their interests in both statutory and constitutional rights. In such a situation, the judge has no choice but to vindicate one right at the expense of the other. In so doing, he or she must be guided by the relative importance attached to the competing rights, both in the statute under consideration and in the Constitution.89 Further guidance can be found in considering the prac- tical consequences of the decision, one way or the other.90 The plausibility of Ngoepe JP’s argument is enhanced by the fact that the main judgments in the Serole and Buhrmann cases are all premised on the closest thing to a clear mistake of law one is ever likely to encounter, viz the view that it was never the intention of the legislature when enacting the ESTA to confer servitudinal rights on occupiers. On the contrary, section 24(1) of the ESTA provides that ‘[t]he rights of an occupier shall … be binding on a successor in title of an owner or person in charge of the land concerned’. According to the subtraction from the dominium test mentioned earlier, this means that occupiers’ rights are statutory real rights with the same legal effect as registered personal servitudes. Whether motivated by the frustration of its original intention, or because of a superven- ing intention to alter the outcome of the Serole and Buhrmann cases, the legislature quick- ly responded to the Supreme Court of Appeal’s decision in Buhrmann by amending the ESTA so as to make it clear that occupiers enjoyed the right in certain circumstances to bury their relatives on land belonging to someone else. In particular, section 6(2) of the ESTA was Performance of the SA Land Claims Court 213 83 Ibid para 17. 84 Ibid. 85 [1999] 4 All SA 337 (T). 86 Nkosi and another v Buhrmann 2002 (1) SA 372 (SCA). 87 Buhrmann (note 86 above) at 352c and 354c. 88 Ibid 351a-e. 89 In this regard, Ngoepe JP argues that secs 5 and 6 of the ESTA, together with other sections, ‘are specifi- cally aimed at making some inroad into [owners’ rights]’, and therefore that the right of ownership must in this instance give way to the right of freedom of religion in sec 5(d) of the ESTA (ibid at 353j). 90 Ibid 354c (dismissing fears that ‘an avalanche of burials might follow’ the granting of the application in the Buhrmann case). 2 1 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E amended by the insertion of a new paragraph, para (dA), which provides that: …[An occupier shall have the right] to bury a deceased member of his or her family who, at the time of that person’s death, was residing on the land on which the occu- pier is residing, in accordance with their religion or cultural belief, if an established practice in respect of that land exists…91 At the same time, ‘established practice’ was defined in s 1(1) as meaning: a practice in terms of which the owner or person in charge or his or her predecessor in title routinely gave permission to people residing on the land to bury deceased members of their family on that land in accordance with their religion or cultural belief.92 The effect of this amendment was to give occupiers who are able to prove that they were rou- tinely granted permission to bury their family members in the past, the right to do so, without the permission of the landowner.93 As argued earlier, although this amendment does not show that the LCC, the Full Bench of the TPD and the Supreme Court of Appeal, in deciding the Serole and Buhrmann cases, made clear mistakes of law, or that Ngoepe JP’s argument in sup- port of an alternative outcome was plausible, it does indicate that the LCC failed to fulfil the social transformation function allocated to it by the legislature. The possible explanations for this result are themselves worth investigating for what they reveal about the role of courts in new democracies, particularly since, in the case of the LCC, some of the factors that might typ- ically have influenced it were absent. IV The Possible Explanations In all four areas of law discussed in the previous section the LCC handed down decisions that were unfavourable to poor litigants, despite the existence of plausible legal arguments to the contrary. This is most clearly apparent in the Richtersveld case, where a higher court overturned the LCC decision in terms quite dismissive of its reasoning. In the case of spouses and depen- dants’ rights under the ESTA, the LCC restricted the impact of a rule laid down in one of its prior decisions that had been more favourable to the poor, thereby exposing female farm work- ers and their children to the possibility of being evicted through no fault of their own. In the burial rights cases, Ngoepe JP’s dissenting judgment in Buhrmann is indicative of the way that the issue might have been decided in Serole had the LCC not proceeded from an erroneous legal premise. That the LCC’s decision did not accord with the legislature’s social transformation objectives is evidenced by the amendment rapidly effected to the ESTA after the appellate deci- 91 As inserted by sec 7(a) of the Land Affairs General Amendment Act 51 of 2001. 92 Definition of ‘established practice’ inserted by the Land Affairs General Amendment Act 51 of 2001. 93 In an interesting sequel to this story, the constitutionality of this amendment was challenged soon after its enact- ment under the constitutional property clause. See Nhlabati v Fick [2003] 2 All SA 323 (LCC); 2003 (7) BCLR 806 (LCC). Finding that the amendment provided for the uncompensated expropriation of property contrary to sec 25(2) and (3) of the Constitution, the LCC upheld it under the general limitations clause as being a lim- itation on the right to property that was reasonable and justifiable in an open and democratic society. sion in Buhrmann. The Macleantown decision, too, met with a fairly swift legislative response that virtually eliminated the LCC from the restitution process. The fact that the LCC had by this time tacitly overruled its own decision suggests that a plausible pro-poor legal argument had all along been available to it, but was for some reason ignored. The absence of effective legal aid for the rural poor has certainly contributed to the failure of the legislation over which the LCC has jurisdiction to achieve its objectives, but this factor on its own cannot explain anti-poor outcomes in cases where the poor were effectively represented. The absence of an effective legal strategy on the part of poor litigants also does not explain these outcomes, since two of the cases discussed (Richtersveld and Serole) were taken on by experi- enced human rights lawyers, and the others involved areas of law in which the legal strategy pur- sued was initially successful (Conradie) or in which there was no need for a legal strategy because the LCC was simply required to confirm a settlement agreement (Macleantown). Enough at least has been said to suggest that the performance of the LCC must be attribut- able to other factors. If the theoretical model tested in this article is sound, it must be possible to explain the outcomes in these cases by reference to one or more of the three institutional indi- cators identified, these being: the legal culture in which the LCC is operating, the residual influ- ence of common-law rules and forms of legal reasoning, or a desire on the part of the judges for professional respect. The possible role of these indicators in explaining the performance of the LCC is now discussed in turn. (A) THE INFLUENCE OF LEGAL CULTURE (i) Defining South African Legal Culture By far the most comprehensive study of South African legal culture is that by Martin Chanock in The Making of South African Legal Culture 1902-1936: Fear, Favour and Prejudice.94 As its title suggests, this work is mainly a historical study, although it does contain a speculative final chapter in which Chanock considers how the transition to democracy in 1994 might have affected the received legal culture he describes in the rest of his book. For Chanock, ‘a legal cul- ture is made up of an interrelated set of discourses about law: some professional, some admin- istrative, some political, some popular’.95 This is a very broad definition, to which he is driven because of his concern to shift the debate about South African legal culture away from what ‘courts and judges’ do towards the study of bureaucratic behaviour. Chanock thus makes a dis- tinction between professional legal discourse, which he assumes was dominated by legal for- malism,96 and bureaucratic legal discourse, which he argues was legal realist in character.97 He then goes on to discuss in detail the nature of bureaucratic legal culture, reducing the discus- sion of professional legal discourse to a single chapter.98 In the result, Chanock’s study, despite its length and theoretical ambition, has little to contribute to the debate about the nature of pro- fessional legal discourse in South Africa. Unsurprisingly, the most intense period of debate about South African legal culture in the Performance of the SA Land Claims Court 215 94 Published by Cambridge University Press in 2001. 95 Ibid 23. 96 Ibid. 97 Ibid. 98 Ibid chapter 10. 2 1 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E narrow sense occurred during the last decade and a half of apartheid, when liberal legal aca- demics produced a series of studies on the role of lawyers and judges in that system. The best known of these studies are those by Hugh Corder,99 Christopher Forsyth,100 John Dugard,101 Stephen Ellmann,102 David Dyzenhaus,103 and Richard Abel.104 In general, this literature depicts professional legal culture as ‘executive-minded’,105 by which is meant a tendency to defer to the intuited wishes of the executive, whether by formalistic application of clearly artic- ulated rules, or by filling doctrinal gaps with rules that the legal professional perceived to be in line with the executive’s preferred policy choice.106 In relation to judges, the point of this debate was of course to expose or defend the degree of discretion enjoyed by the judiciary when deciding politically controversial cases, and thereby to explore the extent of the opportunities available to judges to soften the impact of apartheid laws. Interestingly, the liberal camp split into two on this issue, with some aca- demics positing the existence of some discretion as the moral justification judges had for staying in office and others the absence of any real discretion as the reason why judges had a moral duty to resign.107 For conservative defenders of the judiciary, of course, the absence of discretion was the very reason why judges could not be charged with complicity in the apartheid system.108 In this way, one section of the liberal camp and the conservative camp may have had a common strategic interest in typifying professional legal discourse as being more committed to legal formalism than it actually was. Certainly, the extreme view that judges are never required to fill doctrinal gaps by resort to policy-reasoning would have been dismissed by professionals of all political stripes.109 Nevertheless, there does seem to be an overwhelming consensus in the literature that professional legal discourse under apartheid, particularly in relation to the interpretation of statutes,110 was predominantly 99 Judges at Work: The Role and Attitudes of the South African Appellate Judiciary, 1910-50 (1984). 100 In Danger for their Talents: A Study of the Appellate Division of the Supreme Court of South Africa from 1950-80 (1985). 101 ‘The Judicial Process, Positivism and Civil Liberty’ (1971) 88 SALJ 181 at 182. See also J Dugard Human Rights and the South African Legal Order (1978). 102 In a Time of Trouble: Law and Liberty in South Africa’s State of Emergency (1992). 103 Hard Cases in Wicked Legal Systems: South African Law in the Perspective of Legal Philosophy (1991) (hereafter Dyzenhaus Hard Cases). See too D Dyzenhaus Truth, Reconciliation and the Apartheid Legal Order (1998) (hereafter Dyzenhaus Truth, Reconciliation and the Apartheid Legal Order). 104 Politics by Other Means: Law in the Struggle against Apartheid, 1980-1994 (1995). 105 The origin of this term appears to be a passage in Lord Atkin’s dissent in Liversidge v Anderson [1952] AC 206. See Dyzenhaus Hard Cases (note 103 above) 93-97. The Liversidge decision later played a central role in the South African Appellate Division’s approach to national security cases, and Lord Atkin’s phrase con- sequently came to be used by liberal legal academics as a convenient label for this approach. See, for exam- ple, Cameron ‘Legal Chauvinism, Executive-Mindedness and Justice: LC Steyn’s Impact on South African Law’ (1982) 99 SALJ 38, and Forsyth (note 100 above) 226-34. 106 Note David Dyzenhaus’s interesting alternative thesis that the South African judiciary under apartheid was not so much ‘executive-minded’ as committed to a doctrine of judicial responsibility that required them to align themselves with the views of the executive (Dyzenhaus Hard Cases (note 103 above) 105). 107 See R Wacks ‘Judges and Injustice’ (1984) 101 SALJ 266; J Dugard ‘Should Judges Resign? A Reply to Professor Wacks’ (1984) 101 SALJ at 286. 108 See A Van Blerk ‘The Irony of Labels’ (1982) 99 SALJ 365 and A Van Blerk Judge and Be Judged (1988). See also LC Steyn ‘Regsbank en Regsfakulteit’ (1967) 30 THRHR at 101. 109 See Forsyth (note 100 above) at 230 (arguing that judicial formalism in South Africa under aparthied was not so much the expression of a firmly held legal theory as a device to ‘conceal the reality of [judicial] choice … from the reader of the judgment’). 110 See Forsyth (note 100 above) at 207 commenting on the use of ‘principle and policy’ in the development of the common law under apartheid. formalistic.111 Even liberal defenders of the judiciary had to concede that the opportunities for softening the impact of apartheid laws by exploiting doctrinal gaps were few and far between.112 This was partly the result of the apartheid legislature’s use of increasingly de- tailed rules. But it was also partly the result of the fact that legal professional discourse cen- sured any overt instances of judicial law making, however well intentioned. The question whether South African legal culture in the narrow sense has begun to change under the influence of the new democratic order has not been extensively studied, but there is some research that touches on this issue indirectly. After the Constitutional Court’s first year of operation, Alfred Cockrell published a much-cited article in which he argued that the Constitutional Court had yet to develop the coherent ‘substantive vision of law’ required by the new Constitution.113 He attributed this failure in large measure to the lag-effect of the judges’ background and training in a rule-bound, ‘formal vision of law’.114 Two years’ later, Karl Klare published an equally celebrated article in which he examined the new modes of legal reasoning required by the South African Constitution, and pondered on the likelihood of these new modes being adopted by the legal profession and judges.115 In a section devoted specifically to legal culture, Klare remarked that ‘[a] visiting U.S. lawyer cannot help but be struck by the conser- vatism of South African legal culture’.116 He went on to explain that what he meant by this was not ‘conservatism’ in the form of political ideology, but ‘cautious traditions of analysis common to South African lawyers of all political outlooks’.117 More recently, Cora Hoexter has defined legal formalism in its South African guise as ‘a judi- cial tendency to attach undue importance to the pigeonholing of a legal problem and to its superficial or outward characteristics; and a concomitant judicial tendency to rely on techni- cality rather than substantive principle or policy, and on conceptualism instead of common sense’.118 As Hoexter notes, this approach to legal interpretation is not necessarily conserva- tive, since a formalistic interpretative strategy can be, and was under apartheid, used to achieve progressive results.119 For the same reason, a formalistic approach to progressive, social legis- Performance of the SA Land Claims Court 217 111 For example, David Dyzenhaus’s account of the South African judiciary’s approach to the interpretation of apartheid legislation dealing with racial segregation and national security distinguishes between two main approaches: a ‘plain fact’ approach and a ‘common law’ approach. He describes the former approach as open to the ‘charge of formalism and mechanism’ (Dyzenhaus Hard Cases (note 103 above) at 58) because of its ten- dency to fill interpretative gaps ‘by deciding the case in accordance with what would jump to the minds of most white South Africans’. Later he states that ‘a blinkered focus on the provisions of the statute’ is a ‘hallmark of the plain fact approach’, one that goes ‘with a doctrine of judicial responsibility which seeks to keep a judge’s moral and political convictions out of interpretation’ (ibid 90). See also D Dyzenhaus Truth, Reconcilation and the Apartheid Legal Order (note 103 above) at 77 (describing the plain fact approach as ‘part of a judicial response pattern … identified’ by Robert Cover as a ‘retreat to a mechanistic formalism’ (quoting R Cover Justice Accused: Antislavery and the Judicial Process (1975) at 232). The common law approach identified by Dyzenhaus is, in my view, equally a retreat to ‘a mechanistic formalism’ in as much as the common law, rather than principled or policy-based reasoning, is used to fill the interpretative gap. 112 See Dugard (note 107 above) at 291 (remarking that there was ‘some room for judicial advancement of human rights in the interstices of the apartheid legal order’). 113 A Cockrell ‘Rainbow Jurisprudence’ (1996) 12 SAJHR at 1. 114 Ibid 35. 115 Karl E Klare ‘Legal Culture and Transformative Constitutionalism’ (1998) 14 SAJHR at 146. 116 Ibid 168. 117 Ibid. 118 ‘Contracts in Administrative Law: Life after Formalism?’ (2004) 121 SALJ 595-618. 119 See Abel (note 104 above) at 490 (referring to legal formalism as a ‘two-edged sword’, which ‘could be invoked by the state as well as against it’, and to the fact that ‘parties and courts opportunistically used and ignored legal formalism’). 2 1 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E lation is not necessarily an indication of conservative judicial politics, inasmuch as the formal application of a clearly stated pro-poor rule should in theory produce a pro-poor outcome. Where the legislation is unclear, however, or where it requires judges to engage in substantive reasoning as part of the formulated rule, a culture of legal formalism may work against the achievement of the objectives of a social transformation law. The next section explores this question in greater detail. (ii) Legal Formalism and the Interpretation of Social Transformation Statutes The literature on legal formalism distinguishes between legal formalism as a legal theory and legal formalism as a mode of legal reasoning.120 The two senses of the term are said to share a common ‘attitude to verbally formulated rules which both seeks to disguise and to minimize the need for [decision-maker] choice, once the general rule has been laid down’.121 The charge of legal formalism is almost always pejorative,122 and consequently no serious scholar is said to espouse this theory, at least in its pure form.123 Rather, legal formalism is said to consist either in the mistaken belief ‘that a particular abstract legal norm can generate a particular subrule’, or in a ‘general tendency to overestimate the capacity of norms … to generate subrules by deduction’.124 A tendency of this sort was the tendency against which the legal realist move- ment in the United States is said to have reacted in the early part of the last century.125 In juris- dictions where legal realism is the dominant professional legal culture, such as the United States after the attack on formalism, legal formalism survives in individual instances of legal inter- pretation.126 In the context of adjudication, legal formalism in the narrow sense may manifest itself in one of two main ways: either as a genuine mistake regarding the ambit of the rule being applied, such that the judge sincerely believes that the outcome of the case is determined by deduction from the rule being applied; or as a discursive strategy used to mask an outcome that is moti- vated by a policy choice that the judge for some or other reason does not wish to articulate expressly. Where adjudication occurs against the background of a professional legal culture that censures overt judicial law making, such as that prevailing in South Africa, the reason for not disclosing a policy choice need not be the sinister reason that the judge wishes to legislate by stealth. It may simply be that the judge has been so immersed in a culture of justifying decisions by deduction from general rules that he or she is incapable, for professional reasons, of justify- ing decisions in any other way. It follows that, when interpreting a legislative rule, any ambiguity in the formulation of the rule, or any under-inclusiveness of the rule when applied to the facts, will create a kind of pro- 120 See D Kennedy A Critique of Adjudication (fin de siècle) (1997) at 105-07; HLA Hart The Concept of Law (1961) 121-150; NE Simmonds Central Issues in Jurisprudence: Justice, Law and Rights (1986) at 87 (dis- cussing Hart’s distinction between formalism and rule-scepticism). 121 Hart (note 120 above) at 126. 122 Ibid (referring to the ‘vice known to legal theory as formalism or conceptualism’). See also F Schauer Playing by the Rules: A Philosophical Examination of Rule-Based Decision-Making in Law and in Life (1991) 214 (referring to the ‘argument for what is often pejoratively referred to as “formalism”’). 123 See, however, BA Garner (ed) Black’s Law Dictionary (7ed 1999) at 904, which lists Christopher Columbus Langdell and Lon Fuller as legal formalists. 124 Kennedy (note 120 above) at 106. 125 Brian Bix Jurisprudence: Theory and Context (1996) at 152-53. 126 Kennedy (note 120 above) at 106-7. fessional tension in the mind of a judge committed to legal formalism, all the more so where the rule occurs in a social transformation statute. By definition, the issue to be decided in a case involving the interpretation of this sort of statute will be the extent to which the legislature intended to transform the social order, either directly or by amendment of the existing legal rules. Faced by a situation of legal indeterminacy, the instinctive reaction of a judge committed to legal formalism is to try to close the doctrinal gap by falling back on the maxim of statuto- ry interpretation that the statute amends the existing legal rules only to the extent that it does so expressly. In many cases, this means that, rather than filling the doctrinal gap with a princi- ple-based or policy-derived rule, the judge will come to the conclusion that the pre-existing legal rules (of common law or statute) have not been amended. Of course, this does not mean that the doctrinal gap left by the social transformation statute remains unfilled. It simply means that it is filled by the pre-existing legal rules. Karl Klare’s observation about the role of ‘cautious traditions of analysis common to South African lawyers of all political outlooks’127 makes much the same point: it is not that judges committed to legal formalism are necessarily conservative, it is that their professional training and, in particular, their aversion to policy-reasoning, often drives them to fill doctrinal gaps in social transformation statutes with pre-existing legal rules. The distinction Klare draws between judicial ideology and the dominant professional legal culture in South Africa is, I think, an important one for the assessment of the performance of the LCC. As noted earlier, the LCC judges all had prior careers as human rights lawyers or lawyers engaged in what might loosely be termed ‘progressive’ causes, such as the education of black lawyers or the national peace process. Although there is probably a range of political thought represented on the Court, none of the judges can be described as a political conservative. Nevertheless, they were all trained in the apartheid era, and can therefore be expected to have absorbed the then dominant profes- sional legal culture, a culture in which respect for the techniques of deductive reasoning tend- ed to outweigh resort to principles or policy arguments. If this is correct, what we should expect to find in the LCC’s judgments is a tendency to shun principles and policy arguments in favour of strained deductions from general rules. (iii) Revisiting the Cases The Macleantown decision, as we have seen, is characterised by the high value placed by the Court on formal compliance with the Restitution Act and an almost wilful disregard of the con- sequences of its decision for the restitution process. The LCC must have been aware, as it wrote its judgment, of the painfully slow progress the Commission on Restitution of Land Rights had been making in settling claims. And yet it chose to hand down a highly technical judgment in which the fact that the parties were all in agreement as to how the claim should be settled was given less weight than the question whether the enforcement of the settlement agreement would be a competent order for the Court to make. Had the deficiencies in the settlement agreement been substantial, or the likely impact on the parties and other affected persons of the endorse- ment of a technically deficient agreement severe, this might have been a reasonable approach for the Court to have taken. But neither of these factors was present. Nor did the Court attempt, in the fashioning of its order, to balance its concern for technical correctness with the need to assist the Commission in the performance of its duties. Rather, the relationship that the Performance of the SA Land Claims Court 219 127 Klare (note 115 above) at 168. 2 2 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E Court sought to construct with the Commission was that of hierophant and acolyte, with the Court initiating the Commission into the sacred mysteries of the law. This approach is very typ- ical of a professional legal culture in which judges’ legitimacy is built on an assumed absence of discretion in the face of determinate rules. The problem confronting the LCC in the Macleantown case, however, was that the Resti- tution Act was unclear on what its role in enforcing settlement agreements should be. As we have seen, section 14(3) of the Act (as originally formulated) simply set out the procedure that the Commission had to follow in referring settlement agreements to the Court, and section 14(6) provided that the Court should refuse to endorse a settlement agreement if the proper procedure had not been followed. But by what criteria the Court should decide whether or not to enforce a settlement agreement the Restitution Act did not say. Faced with this doctrinal gap, the judges’ professional training led them to supply a rule as if by logical deduction from the statute. Since the enforcement of a settlement agreement amounts to the making of a court order, the Court reasons, ‘the Court can only make a settlement agreement an order of the Court if it is a competent order of the Court in terms of the Act’.128 This is a neat syllogism, but the rule the Court thereby derives is hardly dictated by the Restitution Act in the manner the Court would have us believe. The closest the Court in Macleantown gets to policy reasoning is in its statement that the consequence of the enforcement of the settlement agreement would be ‘the transfer of land rights either to dispossessed black families or to a community’.129 This consequence of course justifies taking its duty to enforce settlement agreements seriously. But the degree of time and resources invested in ensuring that settlement agreements under the Restitution Act are techni- cally correct obviously has to be weighed against the total number of claims lodged, the aver- age time and resources available for the settlement of each claim, and the political context in which the restitution process is taking place. These are all factors that a court more disposed towards filling doctrinal gaps by resort to policy reasoning might have seen fit to mention. That the LCC does not mention these factors is a function of the relative weight accorded by South African professional legal culture to deductive reasoning vis-à-vis policy reasoning. The influence of South African legal culture is also evident in the LCC’s decision in the Richtersveld case, although here it is apparent that a formalistic mode of reasoning was used to justify an outcome that appears to have been motivated by policy considerations. As noted earlier, the issue of the recognition of the doctrine of aboriginal title in South Africa is a high- ly controversial one, since the recognition of this doctrine would call into question the validity of a great many title deeds. Rather than confronting this policy question head on, the LCC in the Richtersveld case deploys a highly formalistic argument around the question of the recog- nition of aboriginal title to decide the case against the claimant community. In this instance, the culture of legal formalism is less a straightjacket from which the Court is unable to escape, than a convenient disguise for the policy choice the Court feels unable openly to articulate. The situation confronting the Court in the Conradie and Klaasen cases was somewhat dif- ferent. It will be recalled that the legislative history leading up to the enactment of the ESTA was one in which a late change had been made to a fundamental principle underlying the statute, namely whether to treat women and children living on commercial farms as protected occupiers in their own right, or as secondary occupiers with special protection. In the nature of 128 Macleantown (note 26 above) 1276I-J. 129 Ibid 1276G. last-minute amendments, the conversion of the statute to one based on the former principle was not perfectly realised by the legislative drafter, leaving a number of textual traces of the latter principle at the level of rule formulation. It is these textual traces to which the Court referred in the Klaasen judgment, after having initially upheld the occupiers-in-their-own-right principle in Conradie. Of particular interest here is the Court’s about-face on the question whether a female farm worker, who is herself employed by the farmer, is an occupier in her own right. In Conradie these were the precise facts that presented themselves for decision, and the Court seemingly had little trouble in deciding that the principle underpinning the ESTA was that each person should be treated as an occupier in his or her own right, and accordingly that a woman could not be evicted merely in consequence of her husband’s actions. This of course produced an anomaly in that the husband, although in principle liable to eviction, could not in fact be evicted because his wife’s right to family life provided an alternative legal basis on which he could remain on the farm. In Klaasen, the Court, whilst acknowledging the Conradie situation as an exception to the general rule,130 later refers to exactly this situation as an example of one of the ‘incongruities’ that follows from reading the ESTA as being based on the principle that family members of an occupier are occupiers in their own right.131 In particular, the incongruity is said to consist in the fact that, if family members are recognised as occupiers in their own right, they ‘will be allowed to remain on the farm, and as part of their right to family life, they will be allowed to bring the evicted farm labourer back to live with them’.132 Instead of confronting this incon- gruity head on by weighing the competing interests involved, the LCC resorts to the legal for- malist mantra that ‘[t]his could never have been the intention of the legislature.’133 But of course it was, at least to the extent that the legislature could be said to have applied it mind in advance to this particular situation. In Conradie, by contrast, when confronted by the ‘incongruous’ result produced by the occu- piers-in-their-own right principle, the Court simply states that the landowner will have to seek ‘other remedies in respect of [the husband’s] misbehaviour’.134 What is going on here? Is the difference in outcome simply a function of the fact that the Conradie and Klaasen judgments were handed down by different judges, one of whom may be more ideologically predisposed to the kind of social transformation envisaged by the ESTA than the other? Or was it because the facts in Conradie (where the husband was clearly prone to violence) drove the Court to articu- late a broad equitable principle that it later regretted? It seems to me that the two judgments are best explained by the fact that the last-minute amendments to the ESTA effected an imper- fect conversion of that statute at the level of detailed rules from a statute based on the princi- ple of primary and secondary occupiers to one based on the occupiers-in-their-own-right prin- ciple. When confronted by the resultant contradiction at the level of detailed rules, what the Court in Klaasen did was to fall back on the organising principle that most closely resembled the principle that had always been applied at common law, namely that the spouse and depen- dants of a male occupier should be treated as secondary occupiers. The fact that this choice of principle exposed women and children living on commercial farms to eviction through no fault of their own was a consequence that lay outside the Court’s field of reference. Why? Because Performance of the SA Land Claims Court 221 130 Klaasen (note 71 above) para 24. 131 Ibid para 32. 132 Ibid. 133 Ibid. 134 Conradie (note 67 above) para 21(vii). 2 2 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E consequentialist, policy-based reasoning was a form of reasoning with which the Court was not particularly comfortable. To have adopted the occupiers-in-their-own-right principle would have required the Court to expose itself to the possibility of having to legislate afresh each time a case came before it in which the contradiction produced an anomaly. Far better for the Court to adopt the secondary-occupiers principle since that principle came ready-to-use with a set of accepted common-law rules. Once again, it would seem, the prevailing professional legal cul- ture in South Africa provides an adequate explanation for the poor, pro-poor performance of the Court. The three areas of law discussed thus far represent three different types of legal indetermi- nacy that the LCC resolved in ways that obviated the need to engage in policy reasoning. In Macleantown, the Restitution Act was silent as to the role of the Court in supervising settle- ment agreements, and the Court filled the gap with a rule that it purported to deduce from the language of the statute, but which was in actual fact a rule of its own making. In the Richtersveld case, faced with the awkward uncertainty in the Restitution Act as to what to do about aboriginal title claims, the Court made a policy choice and then disguised this choice by resort to formalistic reasoning. And in Klaasen, as we have just seen, the Court decided between two competing principles by choosing the one that most closely resembled the principle appli- cable at common law. The Serole case produced a fourth type of legal indeterminacy that the LCC dealt with in much the same way. In this case, it will be recalled, the Court was asked to vindicate one of two competing rights: the landowner’s property right in a patch of ground, and the occupiers’ right to freedom of religion and culture. As Ngoepe JP’s minority judgment in the Buhrmann case shows, there was really no way of deciding this issue other than to declare the contradiction, and to seek a principled and policy-based justification for choosing one right in preference to the other. Instead what the LCC (together with the Full Bench of the TPD and the Supreme Court of Appeal) did was to eschew a potentially radical in effect, but textually supported, interpretation of the ESTA (as conferring real rights on occupiers), so as to bolster the landown- er’s property right at the expense of the occupiers’ right to freedom of religion and culture. Once again, the mantra of the cautious judge – that the legislature could not have intended to alter the common law to the extent suggested135 – is used to close the doctrinal gap and justi- fy the rule-choice without resort to policy reasoning. And once again, what looks at first blush like an outcome motivated purely by conservative judicial politics, is really an outcome influ- enced by the prevailing professional legal culture. (B) OTHER INSTITUTIONAL INDICATORS The theoretical model tested in this article posits two other institutional indicators that may condition the social transformation performance of courts: the influence of the common law, and judges’ desire for professional respect. Both of these indicators have, however, already been subsumed under the influence of professional legal culture as defined. In a culture dominated by legal formalism, the influence of the common law is registered as a source of ready-made legal rules on which the cautious judge may rely in order to fill doctrinal gaps, without engag- ing in policy reasoning. Confronted by a situation of legal indeterminacy when interpreting a 135 Serole (note 81 above) para 16 (holding that the right to establish a grave is ‘not the kind of right which the legislature intended to grant to occupiers’). social transformation statute, the cautious judge, rather than justifying his or her decision on policy grounds, does one of two things: either he or she alludes to the ambiguity and fills it with a pre-existing legal rule drawn from the common law, or the judge makes the ambiguity disap- pear by straining the language of the statute to produce a gap-filling rule. The common law, in other words, exerts an influence on the social transformation performance of courts in a legal formalist culture by providing a fallback source of legal rules in cases of legal indeterminacy. Since the statute being applied is by definition a statute that attempts to transform the existing social order by transforming the rules that regulate it, the result is almost always a ‘conserva- tive’ result, in the sense that the existing social and legal order remains unchanged. But this does not necessarily mean that the judges who are responsible for such results are themselves con- servative, or that the results are attributable in some mechanistic way to the influence of con- servative judicial politics. The influence of the judges’ natural desire for professional respect has also already been accommodated in the concept of professional legal culture used here. It is precisely because the judges of the LCC want to be recognised as professionally competent that they are susceptible to the influence of professional legal culture. The fact that the judges of the LCC were not drawn from the ranks of practising advocates or sitting judges only exacerbates this situation, since the absence of prior approval from their peers provides all the more reason for the judges to want to establish their professional credentials. This influence emerges clearly in the highly technical decision in Macleantown, which probably had a lot to do with the LCC’s desire to establish its credibility in its first decision. The same desire for professional respect might explain the Court’s reluctance to depart from established forms of civil procedure in relation to the citation of spouses and dependants in actions for ejectment under the ESTA. In the other cases, the desire for professional respect is less obviously present, but exerts an indirect influ- ence in the manner just described, ie as a necessary condition for the influence exerted by the prevailing professional legal culture. V Conclusion This article has sought to test a theoretical model of the role of courts in social transformation through examining the performance of the South African Land Claims Court in four areas of law. The LCC was chosen for analysis because it provided an opportunity to eliminate some of the variables that typically condition the performance of courts in this context. If the model is sound, the elimination of non-relevant variables should not affect the capacity of the model to explain the observed phenomenon. In this case, however, the further problem is that the observed phenomenon – the record of the LCC in the four areas chosen for analysis – is in the nature of a sub-atomic particle that cannot be measured without distorting the result. In order to guard against this danger, the methodology pursued in this article has been to lower the stan- dard of persuasion that is ordinarily required in acts of legal interpretation. Rather than argu- ing that the cases studied here were wrongly decided, this article has argued that they ignored or rejected pro-poor legal arguments that could have been used to justify an alternative out- come. In some cases, independent evidence of the existence of pro-poor legal arguments is found in the form of minority or appellate judgments. In others, the legislature’s response to decisions of the LCC is used to crosscheck its performance in the weak political sense. Having made out the case for the poor, pro-poor performance of the LCC in this way, this article set out to explain that performance in terms of the indicators suggested by the model. Performance of the SA Land Claims Court 223 2 2 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E For various reasons, all but the so-called ‘institutional indicators’ were capable of elimination, and the main institutional indicator – the influence of professional legal culture – was defined in such a way as to incorporate the other two (the influence of the common law and the judges’ desire for professional respect). Although there is some difference in emphasis, the literature on South African legal culture in the narrow sense portrays that culture as predominantly legal for- malist in character. Legal formalism was defined as a tendency at a discursive level to assume or pretend that legal rules are capable of producing determinate outcomes in every case, with- out resort to policy reasoning. This being so, the theoretical model suggested that the judgments studied here should be explicable as instances in which the LCC’s allegiance to the discursive methods and professional standards of legal formalism outweighed any ideological predisposi- tion it might have had to decide the cases differently. Conversely, in the event that the judges’ private political views are adduced as possible explanations of the outcomes in these cases, adherence to legal formalism should be capable of providing an adequate alternative explana- tion. Tested in this way, the theoretical model survived contradiction. In all four areas of law examined here the anti-poor outcomes were adequately explained in terms of the LCC’s resort to quasi-deductive reasoning when faced by doctrinal gaps in the rules relevant to the decision. In the Macleantown case the gap consisted in the legislature’s failure to regulate the precise function of the Court in enforcing settlement agreements under the Restitution Act. In the Richtersveld case, the gap took the form of a crucial ambiguity surrounding the application of the Restitution Act to claims based on the doctrine of aboriginal title. In the remaining two areas, the doctrinal gap was produced by competing principles (Conradie and Klaasen) and contradictory rights (Serole). In every case, rather than filling the gap by reasoning on the basis of principle or policy, the LCC attempted to fill it by quasi-deductive methods typical of the cul- ture of legal formalism in which it is operating. This result confirms the soundness of the theoretical model to this extent. At the same time it provides an insight into the way in which South African professional legal culture continues to exert a restraining influence on the capacity of courts to be used as agents of social trans- formation. If there is a single, ironic lesson to be learned from this study, it is that the same methods that were used under apartheid to turn the courts into agents of that malevolent pol- icy – the use of detailed prescriptive rules – might have to be used to ensure that the courts play an effective role in democratic social transformation. Of course, this recommendation itself places too much legal formalist faith in the capacity of rules to produce determinate results. Until such time as South African professional legal culture has changed from one dominated by a ‘formal vision’ of law to one dominated by a ‘substantive vision’,136 however, there appears to be little alternative. 136 Cockrell (note 113 above) 35. On Social and Economic Justice in South Africa Today: A Theological Perspective on Theoretical Paradigms D J S M I T Department of Systematic Theology and Ecclesiology, Stellenbosch University I Introduction The present research project is developed around two hypotheses about social and economic transformation in South Africa. The first is that theory matters, that theoretical frameworks and paradigms have an influence upon the developments taking place within and around them, more specifically, that prevailing and dominant theoretical paradigms concerning social and economic justice in South Africa today have an influence on the implementation of policy, leg- islation and general transformation. The second is that theoretical drag may be partly respon- sible for slower delivery on social and economic justice than the Constitution promises, more specifically, that the theoretical framework in which present transformations have to take place fails in many ways to support the necessary implementation, thereby frustrating rather than facilitating social and economic justice. Christian theology – probably similar to law and economy – does not speak with one voice. Historically, the dominant theological traditions – including the Orthodox, Catholic, and Protestant traditions – have developed different views concerning ethical approaches. This also applies to theories of justice. Even within these traditions themselves – for example Pro- testantism, or even more specifically the Reformed faith – different approaches complement and often contradict one another. There is no single authoritative theological position regarding the- ories and practices of social, economic or legal justice. All claims are therefore modest and con- textual, and reflect specific traditions, experiences and perspectives. The following comments are accordingly also made from a specific perspective, namely that of Protestant and ecumeni- cal developments during the last century, particularly associated with the confessional tradition of Barmen and experiences of resistance against injustices in Germany, Latin America and apartheid-South Africa.1 1 For the confessional tradition of Barmen, including theological understandings of the notion of justice from the so-called Confessional Church Struggle in Germany, see K Barth Texte zur Barmer Theologischen Erklärung (1984), A Burgsmüller and R Weth (eds) Die Barmer Theologische Erklärung: Einführung und Dokumentation (1983), and E Busch Die Barmer Thesen 1934 - 2004 (2004). For a helpful discussion of the reception of the notion of ‘the preferential option for the poor’ from Latin American church struggles for social and economic justice in ecumenical documents, see H Bedford-Strohm Vorrang für die Armen: auf dem Weg zu einer theologischen Theorie der Gerechtigkeit (1993). For the church struggle against the the- ology of apartheid and specifically the historical context and thrust of the Confession of Belhar, see GD Cloete and DJ Smit A Moment of Truth: The Confession of the Dutch Reformed Mission Church (1984). 2 2 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E From this specific theological perspective, the two hypotheses seem very plausible, and some of their implications are of direct importance to theology and the church. To put it in theological- ethical and ecclesiological language, it seems possible to argue, firstly, that the way the public opinion thinks and speaks about justice will have a definite impact on any possible structural implementation of social and economic justice (‘theory matters’), and secondly, that many of the processes needed to implement more social and economic justice in South Africa today may be hindered by the way the public opinion thinks and speaks about justice (‘theoretical drag’). Therefore, changing the way the South African public opinion thinks and speaks about justice – the prevailing and dominant theoretical framework – may contribute toward overcoming the present theoretical drag and the slow pace of implementing social and economic justice. Given the nature and the calling of the Christian church, as seen from this specific theological perspec- tive, together with the social position and role of the church in the South African society today, it may be argued that the church should and could make a meaningful contribution in this regard. The following paragraphs will develop these general claims somewhat more fully. II ‘Theory Matters’ From this specific theological perspective, it is of crucial importance to affirm an intimate rela- tionship between justice (that is, legal justice, but also political, economic and social justice) and ethics (and therefore morality, and theology). Where total separation between law and ethics has historically developed (particularly in Western modernity’s separation of legality and moral- ity, especially since Kant), this development is regarded as one-sided and suspect, from this the- ological viewpoint. Such varieties of separation would include diverse forms of legal positivism, but also different theoretical claims to exclude moral and ethical discourses from economic and political rationalities.2 Some of the important reasons for affirming such a relationship between law and ethics are given both with the nature and content of the Christian faith, as well as with historical experi- ences of large-scale injustices. Such historical experiences include the failure of twentieth-cen- tury legal systems and political and economic rationalities to deal adequately with the social injustices they faced. From this specific theological perspective, however, this relationship between law and ethics is not and should not be construed as one of identity, for example by subsuming the one in the other. Instead, it is regarded as of crucial importance to distinguish between legal, moral, ethi- cal and therefore theological discourses.3 All forms of identification between law and ethics that have historically developed, including all (theological, philosophical and legal) theories of nat- 2 For an extensive theological critique of these forms of separation, see W Huber Gerechtigkeit und Recht: Grundlinien Christlicher Rechtsethik (1996). For a related but philosophical treatment, see many of the later works of Jürgen Habermas, including for example his article ‘Vom pragmatischen, ethischen und moralischen Gebrauch der praktischen Vernunft’ in J Habermas Erläuterungen zur Diskursethik (1991) at 100-118; J Habermas Faktizität und Geltung: Beiträge zur Diskurstheorie des Rechts und des demokratis- chen Rechtsstaats (1992). 3 For different ways of maintaining such distinctions, see eg J Habermas Erläuterungen zur Diskursethik (1991); N Luhmann Ausdifferenzierung des Rechts: Beiträge zur Rechtssoziologie und Rechtstheorie (1981); W Huber Gerechtigkeit und Recht (1996); as well as the influential work of the systematic theolo- gian also working within this Reformed tradition, M Welker ‘Moral, Recht und Ethos in evangelisch-theol- ogischer Sicht’ in W Härle and R Preul (eds) Ethik und Recht (2002) at 67-82. ural law, are seen as deeply problematic and even dangerous, since they can easily lead to ide- ological misuse. Any form of moralising of the law, politics or the economy is rejected. This theological perspective, therefore, will show affinity with theoretical paradigms and the- ories of justice that seek ways between positivism on the one hand and natural law on the other hand, respectively making absolute claims for what is on the one hand and for what should be on the other hand. What could the contribution be of such a ‘critical theology of law’?4 Broadly speaking, it will seek to contribute both loyalty to, as well as criticism and reform of the existing legal, political and economic systems. It will both strongly support the existing justice and, wherever and whenever it is regarded as necessary, plead and work for better and more justice. Both these approaches – loyalty and criticism – are deeply embedded in the Biblical and Christian tradi- tions, for example with its well-known command to obey all authority, yet if necessary to obey God more than any form of human authority. This obviously raises many questions, including questions concerning the theory of justice involved. When should loyalty become criticism and reform? What would be the theological norm? Which criteria of justice are used to discern between moments of loyalty and moments of criticism, between conditions calling for support and conditions calling for renewal and even resistance?5 Is there – to put it differently – a specifically theological theory of justice?6 Theological Perspective on Theoretical Paradigms 227 4 This is for example the way that Huber characterises his own approach, see Huber (note 2 above) at 17, 26-27, 97-106. He explains: ‘Die erste christlicher Rechtsethik war deshalb nicht nur eine Ethik der Rechtsloyalität, … sondern sie war zugleich eine Ethik des zivilen Ungehorsams: ‘Man muss Gott mehr gehorchen als den Menschen’. Damit ist dem christlichen Nachdenken über das Recht eine kritischer Impuls mitgegeben, der freilich in der Geschichte des Christentums allzu häufig verdrängt wurde. Eine theologische Beschäftigung mit dem Recht die jene Anfänge nicht verdrängt, kann nur die Gestalt einer kritischen Theologie des Rechts annehmen. Gerade so kann sie zu einer kritischen Theorie des Rechts beitragen. … Damit ist auch die bestimmende Frage dieses Buches genannt. Es lässt sich von folgender Überzeugung leiten: Eine Rekonstruktion der Sphäre des Rechts muss bei der Situation derer beginnen, die unter den spez- ifisch modernen Formen der Rechtlosigkeit leiden. Nicht das Stöhnen der Wohlhabenden unter der Verrechtlichung der Industriegesellschaft, sondern das Leiden der Unterdrückten und Entrechteten unter Ungerechtigkeit steht am Anfang. Eine kritische Theologie des Rechts beginnt mit den Ausgeschlossenen und Eingesperrten, die politischer Willkür ausgeliefert sind. Sie beginnt mit denen, die sich in ihrem eigenen Land nicht mehr zu Hause wissen und in der Fremde Asyl suchen. Sie beginnt mit den Diskriminierten, die unter einer rassistischen Gewaltherrschaft leben müssen. Sie beginnt mit den Opfern schneller wirtschaftlicher Entwicklung, die sich häufig mit einer autoritären Staatsordnung verbindet. Sie beginnt mit dem Blick auf Menschen, denen in ideologisch beherrschten Ländern das Recht der Meinungsfreiheit geraubt wird. Sie beginnt mit der Perspektive von Frauen, denen in männlich bestimmten Gesellschaften Selbstverwirklichung und Gleichheit vorenthalten werden. Sie beginnt mit denen, die in reichen Industriestaaten dem Modernisierungsprozess weichen müssen und in die Arbeitslosigkeit gedrängt werden. Für sie alle hat das Recht nur Bedeutung, wenn es in den Dienst der Gerechtigkeit tritt, auf die sie hoffen. Wenn dies die bestimmende Perspective auf das Recht ist, wird es freilich unmöglich, Recht und Ethik – die Frage nach dem, was gilt, und die Frage nach dem, was gut ist – voneinander zu trennen. Eben diese Trennung aber bildete einen entscheidenden Schritt in der Ausbildung des neuzeitlichen Rechtsverständnisses. Müssen wir dieses Rechtsverständnis hinter uns lassen? Stehen wir vor einem Epochenwechsel?’ – This then becomes the leading question of his extensive historical and systematic reflections. 5 In a recent key collection of essays edited by P Dabrock et al Kriterien der Gerechtigkeit: Festschrift für Christofer Frey zum 65. Geburtstag (2003), published in honour of the German ethicist Christofer Frey, three theological approaches to justice are for example discussed. A first section on the foundations of justice (Begründungen) offers firstly Old and New Testament perspectives on justice, followed by discussions on jus- tice in the writings of Martin Luther and in evangelical ethics, amongst others. An important contribution by the ethicist Johannes Fischer (‘Jenseits reiner Normativität: Skizze einer theologisch-ethischen Annäherung and die Gerechtigkeitsthematik’ in P Dabrock et al (eds) Kriterien der Gerechtigkeit (2003)) provides a synopsis of current theological-ethical theory on justice. A second (and the largest) section investigates how these various 2 2 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E For this specific perspective, theology does not claim to have its own (alternative) theory of jus- tice.7 Rather, it seeks to engage with existing theoretical frameworks by drawing on its own sources and resources. Drawing on these sources and resources, this theology hopes to con- tribute to some broad theoretical orientation concerning justice that could be helpful in for- mulating law, in evaluating law, and in evaluating the implementation of law. This theology would further support political and economic attempts to implement, practice and embody such forms of justice and join forces with those criticising and resisting failures to embody such forms of justice. In this respect theology can certainly play a role in the present research project. Firstly, both Old and New Testament records can offer valuable orientation and perspective; secondly, the Christian tradition of interpretation can provide instructive developments and case studies; and thirdly, recent and contemporary ecumenical discussions may help to discern critical issues and insights. Research into all three these fields of inquiry (biblical, historical, systematic) could play an important role in developing theology’s own voice and particular contribution.8 Some well-known examples from these, often conflicting histories of interpretation could suffice: understanding the nature and role of justice according to the complex and manifold New Testament traditions;9 understanding justice against the background of the Sermon on the Mount;10 understanding the relationship between justice and love, historically often falsely con- insights are to be applied in a number of social disciplines (Anwendungen), that is in ecological theory, in bio- genetics, in medicine, in just war theory, in matters of asylum seeking, in economy, labour and business, and in family studies. The third and final section (Vermittlungen) deals specifically with how these applications are to be communicated to the public, particularly through visual and audio media, through religious education and through the diaconate of the church – themes of special importance for this research project, which also involves questions of communication and the formation of public opinion. 6 The question whether there is something like a theological theory of justice is often acknowledged and dis- cussed as a very complex and controversial matter. This is demonstrated, for instance, in two successive studies by the respected North American ethicist Karen Lebacqz. In Six Theories of Justice: Perspectives from Philosophical and Theological Ethics (1986), she discusses various theological and philosophical views on justice. She compares influential positions such as John Stuart Mill’s utilitarianism, John Rawls’ contract theory and Robert Nozick’s ‘entitlement’ view with responses from Catholic, Protestant and Liberation per- spectives. She emphasises that different people mean different things by justice and that it is, therefore, an illusive concept – without one single theological solution or approach. In a subsequent collection, K Lebacqz Justice in an Unjust World: Foundations for a Christian Approach to Justice (1987), she attempts to for- mulate an own theory of justice by relating the righteousness of God to injustice in the world and she draws on Scripture to interpret such injustice. Again, she does not offer a comprehensive theological response to the question of justice. She subsequently uses concrete examples to demonstrate how ‘justice’ can be brought about ‘in an unjust world’. 7 For popular discussion of this theme from the perspective of Reformed ethics and proclamation, see DJ Smit ‘Reformed Ethics and Economic Justice’ (1996) 37 Nederduitse Gereformeerde Teologiese Tydskrif 438- 455; DJ Smit ‘Oor die Prediking van Regverdiging en Reg’ in BA Müller et al (eds) Riglyne vir Prediking oor Regverdiging en Reg. Woord teen die Lig III/3 (1993) 1-14; DJ Smit ‘Die Droom van Bybelse Geregtigheid’ (1985) 15 Scriptura 51-70. 8 Many theologians have done this and developed their own discussions of justice from a theological per- spective. See for example the classical study by E Brunner Gerechtigkeit: eine Lehre von den Grundgesetzen der Gesellschaftsordnung (1943), as well as the popular W Lienemann Gerechtigkeit (1995), an ethicist from Bern, Switzerland, writing an overview for ecumenical use. 9 See for example H Balz ‘Die Gerechtigkeit der Gerechtfertigten: eine neutestamentliche Skizze’ in P Dabrock et al (eds) Kriterien der Gerechtigkeit (2003) 45-61. 10 In many Christian theological circles, especially since the Enlightenment, the Sermon on the Mount has been a very popular extract or summary of the Biblical teaching and was often used as the only source for strued as exclusive of one another;11 understanding justice against the background of the legal traditions of the Old Testament, an area of research that recently led to major new and valuable insights;12 understanding the complex historical developments in which classical and Biblical the- ories of justice contradicted, but also complemented one another;13 understanding philosophical and legal developments in modernity, in which deliberately secular theories of justice were often developed in direct opposition to ecclesial, theological and often ethical perspectives; understand- ing conflicting theological theories of justice that build respectively on notions of creation, provi- dence, sin, anthropology and eschatology;14 and finally understanding recent ecumenical debates and struggles concerning justice, freedom, liberation, human rights and the dignity of creation.15 It is immediately obvious that such theological research will necessarily have to be inter-discipli- nary, involving scholars from different theological disciplines. What form could such theological contributions to some broad theoretical orientation con- cerning justice take? At the outset, at least six possible forms could perhaps be foreseen. Firstly, this specific theological perspective brings an eschatological (in philosophical terms: Theological Perspective on Theoretical Paradigms 229 Christian ethics. The interpretation of the Sermon on the Mount is, however, complicated and controver- sial, and so also its use in ethical questions. For a discussion see DJ Smit ‘Die Bergrede in die Geskiedenis’ in CW Burger et al (eds) Riglyne vir Prediking oor die Bergrede (1990) at 11-25; DJ Smit ‘Die bergrede en Christelike etiek’ in CW Burger et al (eds) Riglyne vir Prediking oor die Bergrede (1990) at 34-38. 11 A well-known example has been the influential work of the North-American Reformed theologian Reinhold Niebuhr. See for example the four very authoritative studies of his work by LB Gilkey On Niebuhr: A Theological Study (2001); CW Kegley Reinhold Niebuhr, His Religious, Social, and Political Thought (1984); HB Clark Serenity, Courage, and Wisdom: The Enduring Legacy of Reinhold Niebuhr (1994); RH Stone Reinhold Niebuhr: Prophet to Politicians (1981). See also the unpublished doctoral thesis of SM de Gruchy Not Liberation but Justice: An Analysis of Reinhold Niebuhr’s Understanding of Human Destiny in the Light of the Doctrine of the Atonement (1992) DTh thesis, University of the Western Cape, Bellville. 12 The German systematic theologian Michael Welker has written extensively on justice in the legal traditions of the Old Testament, often together with the widely known Old Testament scholars Jan Assmann and Bernhard Janowski. See the collection of essays in J Assmann et al Gerechtigkeit: Richten und Retten in der abendländischen Tradition und ihren altorientalischen Ursprüngen (1998); also M Welker ‘Dynamiken der Rechtsentwicklung in den biblischen Überlieferungen’ in A Aarnio (ed) Rechtsnorm und Rechtswirklichkeit: Festschrift f. Werner Krawietz zum 60. Geburtstag (1993) at 779-795. Another very influential theologian in this field is the Old Testament scholar Frank Crüsemann. See for example the seminal essay F Crüsemann ‘Jahwes Gerechtigkeit im Alten Testament’ (1976) 36 Evangelische Theologie 427-450, as well as the recent collection of essays in his Festschrift, published as C Hardmeier et al (eds) Freiheit und Recht: Festschrift für Frank Crüsemann zum 65. Geburtstag (2003). 13 A well-known example is the influence of Aristotle and the principle of suum quique, via Thomas Aquinas and scholasticism, in Christian theology. See for T Aquinas ‘Treatment of Justice’ in J Porter ‘The Virtue of Justice’ in SJ Pope (ed) The Ethics of Aquinas (2002); as well as the influential A MacIntyre Whose Justice? Which Rationality? (1988), who makes use of conflicting traditions of interpretation of this legacy in con- structing his own argument and position. 14 Both in more general theological discussions of justice, and in the ecumenical debates on the so-called the- ological basis for human rights, the traditional confessional preferences for some of these theological loci often played a determinative role, for example the central vision of the covenant in the World Alliance of Reformed Churches, the doctrine of justification in the Lutheran World Federation and traditions of moral anthropology for the Roman Catholic Bishops. 15 For a helpful overview of the development of ecumenical social thought during the twentieth century, see M Robra Ökumenische Sozialethik (1994); and for the state of the present discussion in the Ecumenical Movement on some of these themes, see U Duchrow ‘Justice’ in N Lossky et al (eds) Dictionary of the Ecumenical Movement (2002) at 627-630; E Weingärtner ‘Human Rights’ in N Lossky et al (eds) Dictionary of the Ecumenical Movement (2002) at 548-551; DJ Smit ‘Liberty/Freedom’ in N Lossky et al (eds) Dictionary of the Ecumenical Movement (2002) 685-688. 2 3 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E teleological) orientation to the discourse. It speaks a language of hope. It reminds everyone of justice not yet real and fulfilled. It thereby moves and inspires agents for justice, and it empow- ers those who suffer under present injustices not to surrender hope and not to accept their lot without struggle and resistance. It calls the church and all believers to keep praying, to long for this justice and to dream of this reign, and therefore to take all possible steps, small as they may be, in witnessing to this coming reality.16 Secondly, because of this eschatological orientation, it strengthens critical and self-critical thought. This theology encourages those involved in working for justice, particularly those in legal, political and economic spheres. It supports all those actors, including legal theorists, prac- titioners and activists, who seek to strengthen theoretical paradigms that will lead to legal, eco- nomic and social transformations and to practical policy implementations that will contribute to serve justice. From the perspective of the Christian faith, it reminds everyone to remain self- critical, to acknowledge that full justice will never be realized historically, and therefore to emphasise that even – and precisely – the best constitutions, laws and catalogues remain open to (self-) critical evaluation and improvement. Thirdly, based on the content of the Biblical traditions, particularly as they have come to be understood in certain twentieth-century contexts of historical injustice, this theological per- spective advocates a view of justice that takes the perspective of those who suffer under such injustices very seriously. Perhaps this is the most characteristic material contribution of the Biblical traditions concerning justice to any contemporary theory of justice. In South Africa, this perspective has, for example, been expressed in the third article of the Belhar Confession, where it is claimed that the Biblical God has been revealed as ‘in a special way the God of the destitute, the poor and the wronged,’17 and that this God calls the church to follow in this way.18 16 For an extended argument on the importance of seeing as first step in the process of ethical decision-mak- ing, also regarding issues of poverty, suffering and social justice, see DJ Smit ‘On Learning to See? A Reformed Perspective on the Church and the Poor’ in P Couture and BJ Miller-McLemore (eds) Suffering, Poverty, and HIV-AIDS (2003) at 55-70. The famous German systematic theologian Jürgen Moltmann has made a major impact on the discussion on justice and eschatology. Throughout his life he has been active- ly involved in human rights debates within ecumenical circles and he wrote extensively on this through the years. Already in his collection J Moltmann The Experiment Hope (1975), he published three articles on racism, human rights and human dignity. A decade later he wrote specifically on human dignity, as the title suggests: J Moltmann On Human Dignity: Political Theology and Ethics (1984). This volume was wholly dedicated to human rights, where he examined, amongst others, the ecumenical debate on human rights, the relationship between Christian faith and human rights, and the right to ‘meaningful work’. In his recent (and somewhat more popular) book J Moltmann God for a Secular Society: The Public Relevance of Theology (1999), he continues these reflections in a section on human rights (117-134), which includes top- ics such as ‘individual and social rights’, ‘economic rights and ecological obligations’ and ‘the world reli- gions in the forum of human rights.’ 17 The third article on justice reads as follows: ‘We believe that God has revealed himself as the One who wish- es to bring about justice and true peace among people; that in a world full of injustice and enmity He is in a special way the God of the destitute, the poor and the wronged and that He calls his Church to follow Him in this; that He brings justice to the oppressed and gives bread to the hungry; that He frees the pris- oner and restores sight to the blind; that He supports the downtrodden, protects the stranger, helps orphans and widows and blocks the path of the ungodly; that for Him pure and undefiled religion is to visit the orphans and the widows in their suffering; that He wishes to teach His people to do what is good and to seek the right; ‘That the Church must therefore stand by people in any form of suffering and need, which implies, among other things, that the Church must witness against and strive against any form of injustice, so that justice may roll down like waters, and righteousness like an ever-flowing stream; Fourthly, it is therefore to be expected that this theological perspective will show a special sensitivity for all those – individuals, groups and categories of people – who suffer forms of injustice, oppression, rejection, exclusion, violation or abuse. For this reason, the church sometimes, under specific historical circumstances, feels itself called to be a voice for the voiceless, a public conscience, an advocate for the oppressed, or a critical, prophetic chal- lenge to authorities and powers.19 Such claims do not imply that the church – in whichever form – has an alternative theory of justice, but only that its own message and the very rea- son for its existence, its faith, involves a calling to care for those who suffer injustices and to plea and act on their behalf. The involvement of the ecumenical church and theology today in issues of economic globalisation provides an instructive example.20 The church does not resist contemporary global transformations in any of their complex forms (whether cultural, political or economic), but is concerned with some of the disastrous effects of economic glob- alisation in its present form, especially the exclusion, marginalisation and triage of many, including many living in Africa today. In asking whether this form of economic life should not concern the faith of Christians – which is the way the major ecumenical bodies, like the World Alliance of Reformed Churches recently in Accra,21 are framing the question – they do not claim to have any alternative theory of economic justice. They do, however, remind everyone of the suffering of many, and of the injustice thereof, and appeal to everyone in positions of (legal, social, economic and political) responsibility and influence to take this suffering seriously. Fifthly, this theological perspective understandably shows a strong affinity for those theories Theological Perspective on Theoretical Paradigms 231 ‘That the Church as the possession of God must stand where He stands, namely against injustice and with the wronged; that in following Christ the Church must witness against all the powerful and privileged who selfishly seek their own interests and thus control and harm others. ‘Therefore, we reject any ideology which would legitimate forms of injustice and any doctrine which is unwilling to resist such an ideology in the name of the gospel’ (in GD Cloete and DJ Smit A Moment of Truth: The Confession of the Dutch Reformed Mission Church (1984) at 1-6). 18 For historical accounts, interpretations and theological reflections on the God-images at stake, see J Botha and P Naude Op Pad met Belhar: Goeie Nuus vir Gister, Vandag en Môre (1998); and the essays DJ Smit ‘Paradigms of Radical Grace’ in C Villa-Vicencio (ed) On reading Karl Barth in South Africa (1988); and DJ Smit ‘… in a special way the God of the destitute, the poor and the wronged…’ in GD Cloete and DJ Smit (eds) (note 17 above) 127-150. 19 Recent history demonstrates various instances where the church understands itself to be a voice for the voiceless. Three such examples are, for instance, the publication of the Dutch Reformed Church in Africa ‘Transition and Poverty’ (1990) 2/90 (Supplement) DRCA Action 1-25; the more recent docu- ment by the Southern African Catholic Church, Economic Justice in South Africa: A Pastoral Statement (1999), but also the very influential German document published jointly by the Evangelical and Catholic Churches, For a Future Founded on Solidarity and Justice: A Statement of the Evangelical Church in Germany and the German Bishops’ Conference on the Economic and Social Situation in Germany (1997). 20 The literature from the ecumenical church is already vast. For three recent contributions from people involved in the Beyers Naudé Centre, see HR Botman ‘Human Dignity and Economic Globalization’ in HR Botman and K Sporre (eds) Building a Human Rights Culture: South African and Swedish Perspectives (2003) at 20-34; M Haspel Protestantische Ethik vor der Herausforderung der Globalisierung (2004); DJ Smit ‘Theologische Ansätze für kirchliches Engagement in Fragen der Globalisierung - Reformierte Perspektiven aus dem Südlichen Afrika’ 2004 Ökumenische Rundschau 160-175. 21 See Covenanting for Justice in the Economy and the Earth, agreed by the General Council, World Alliance of Reformed Churches, 24th General Council, Accra, Ghana, July 30 – August 13, 2004, http://www.warc.org. 2 3 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E of justice in which the dignity of the human person is regarded as central.22 The inalienable worth and dignity of the human person is the boundary that may not be transgressed, the norm that may not be ignored, the ultimate criterion to apply to social, political and economic life together. Again, this is argued on inner-theological grounds, based on the content and thrust of the Biblical message – although it too has been very controversial within theological circles.23 Despite all these historical and even recent theological debates, however, it is fair to claim that 22 The impact of the German ethicist and bishop Wolfgang Huber on the theological debates on human dig- nity, human rights and justice cannot be overstated. He has become the leading theological figure in the field. He made several contributions regarding theological theories of justice, for example W Huber ‘Beten und Tun des Gerechten’ in W Huber and I Tödt (eds) Ethik im Ernstfall: Dietrich Bonhoeffers Stellung zu den Juden und ihre Aktualitat (1982) at 11-22; W Huber ‘Recht im Horizont der Liebe’ in Brandt et al (eds) Ein Richter, ein Bürger, ein Christ: Festschrift für Helmut Simon (1987) at 1045-1058; W Huber ‘Justice, Peace and the Integrity of Creation: A Challenge for Ecumenical Theology’ (1988) 24 Scriptura 1-16; W Huber ‘Menschenrechte - Christenrechte’ in Recht nach Gottes Wort: Menschenrechte und Grundrechte in Gesellschaft und Kirche (1989) at 82-100; W Huber Konflikt und Konsens: Studien zur Ethik der Verantwortung (1990); W Huber ‘Menschenrechte und biblisches Rechtsdenken: ein Versuch’ (1993) 2 Neukirchener Theologische Zeitschrift: Kirche und Israel 144-160; W Huber ‘Die Prediking oor Regverdigheid en Geregtigheid’ in CW Burger (note 10 above) at 15-24; W Huber ‘Gottesrecht und Menschenrechte in gesellschaftspolitischen Entwürfen’ (1995) 32 epd-Dokumentation 55-60; W Huber Rechtfertigung und Recht: über die christlichen Wurzeln der europäischen Rechtskultur (2001). In the process he often reflected on legal theory, law and German constitutional law; see for example W Huber ‘Das Grundgesetz und die Menschenrechte’ (1989) 33 Zeitschrift für Evangelische Ethik 82-85; W Huber ‘Die Menschenrechte und das Grundgesetz: theologische Überlegungen’ in M Pfeiffer (ed) Auftrag Grundgesetz: Wirklichkeit und Perspektiven (1989) at 190-213; W Huber ‘Recht als Beruf: Verantwortung für das Recht im Horizont der Gerechtigkeit’ in U Neumann and L Schulz (eds) Verantwortung in Recht und Moral: Referate der Tagung der Deutschen Sektion der Internationalen Vereinigung für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie (2000) at 39-55 (also published as W Huber ‘Recht als Beruf: Verantwortung für das Recht im Horizont der Gerechtigkeit’ in Limbach et al (eds) Ist der Rechtsstaat auch ein Gerechtigkeitsstaat? Interdisziplinäre Referatsreihe an der Universität Basel (2000) at 31-59). He dealt extensively with the notion of human dignity; see W Huber ‘Die Würde des Menschen ist antastbar: Anfragen aus der Sicht der christlichen Ethik’ (1990) 45 Universitas 852-861; W Huber ‘Menschenrechte/Menschenwürde’ in Theologische Realencyklopädie XXII (1992) at 577-602; W Huber Die tägliche Gewalt: Gegen die Ausverkauf der Menschenwürde (1993) (translated as W Huber Violence: The Unrelenting Assault on Human Dignity (1996)); W Huber ‘Menschenwürde? Gewalt und Intimität als Unterhaltung’ in W Wunden (ed) Öffentlichkeit und Kommunikationskultur (1994) at 181-199; W Huber ‘Lebenswert und Lebensrecht’ (1995) 31 epd-Dokumentation 51-56; W Huber ‘Die Würde des Menschen ist antastbar: Anfragen aus der Sicht der christlichen Ethik’ in S Abarbanell et al (eds) Fernsehzeit (1996) at 185-195; and he regularly published on human rights; see W Huber ‘Human Rights: A Concept and its History’ (1979) 124 Concilium 1-10; W Huber ‘Menschenrechte’ in Staatslexikon Bd. 3 (1987) at 1103-1118; W Huber ‘Menschenrechte’ in L Engel et al (eds) Hoffnung in der Krise: Dokumente einer christlichen Existenz in Südafrika zum 65. Geburtstag von Wolfram Kistner (1988) at 298-311. Together with HE Tödt he published an authoritative study called W Huber and HE Tödt Menschenrechte: Perspektiven einer menschlichen Welt (1977). He also contributed on specific themes, such as the right to protest, for example W Huber Protestantismus und Protest: zum Verhältnis von Ethik und Politik (1987) and the rights of nature, W Huber ‘Rights of Nature or Dignity of Nature?’ (1992) The Annual of the Society of Christian Ethics 43-61. These contributions culminated in his magnum opus, W Huber Gerechtigkeit und Recht (1996). 23 The very influential German theologian Karl Barth, for instance, placed human dignity central in his whole theology. See for example his well-known essay K Barth The Humanity of God (1967) in which he explained this autobiographically. For a fuller discussion of Barth’s views on justice within his approach to ethics, see DJ Smit ‘’... The Doing of the Little Righteousness’ - On Justice in Barth’s view of the Christian life’ in M Welker and C Jarvis (eds) Serving God with Our Minds: Festschrift for Wallace Alston (2004) at 120-145. For human dignity within theology, see also the collection of key essays in I Balderman et al (eds) Menschenwürde: JBTh 15 (2001). Another important collection is a special edition of the ecumenical jour- nal Una Sancta devoted wholly to human dignity: G Voss et al ‘Menschenwürde neu buchstabieren’ (2000) 55 Una Sancta - Zeitschrift für ökumenische Begegnung 97-176. contemporary ecumenical theology is in very strong agreement that the message of the gospel, the good news of the loving and gracious Triune God, affirms in all its aspects the importance, value and dignity of human beings.24 What is human dignity? Can it be defined or described? Is it possible to give material con- tent to the notion of human dignity? Recent and contemporary discussions – for example the debate in the European Convention on the inclusion or exclusion of human dignity in the European Constitution, and its possible material content, should it be included – have shown that this is not really fully possible, even in those circles where people are deeply committed to the notion and dedicated to serve and protect human dignity, to determine its content in any definite way. Still, it is possible to agree on certain characteristics, often defined negatively, for example in the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, suggesting that human beings deserve to be protected from fear and from want. Of course, these are very broad and general guide- lines, and their implementation will always remain open, dependent on concrete interpretations and realities, yet, they are not for that reason without importance and usefulness. From this theological perspective, it is indeed a very helpful guideline, to link human digni- ty to freedom from fear and freedom from want, and to search for means of common life, including economic life, that could contribute to protect human beings – very specific, concrete individuals and groups of human beings, under very specific and concrete conditions – from causes of fear and causes of want that could indeed be prevented. Sixthly, for that reason, contemporary ecumenical theology (after earlier hesitation) also strongly supports theoretical paradigms in which human rights, as the concrete embodiment of the inalienable human dignity, are central.25 This is not a strong claim. It does not claim, for example, that human rights can be based on or deduced from Scripture, or that human rights Theological Perspective on Theoretical Paradigms 233 24 For a popular statement of this conviction, see DJ Smit ‘Oor die God wat Ons Roep’ in Handelinge van die NGK in SA (Wes- en Suid-Kaapland) (2003) at H99-H103. See also various publications from the ecu- menical church, for instance AO Miller (ed) A Christian Declaration on Human Rights: Theological Studies of the World Alliance of Reformed Churches (1977); as well as the special edition of the journal Reformed World on ‘Theology and Human Rights’ with contributions by AD Falconer ‘Pressing the Claims: Reflections in the Theological Basis of Human Rights’ (1998) 48 Reformed World 50-62, J Schaeffer ‘WARC’s Historic Commitments to Justice and Human Rights’ (1998) 48 Reformed World 63-78, and C John ‘Human Rights and the Churches: The New Challenges’ (1998) 48 Reformed World 79-96; see also the earlier, but popular statement by the Reformed Ecumenical Council RES Testimony on Human Rights (1983). 25 See for instance the study by the influential ethicist M Honecker Das Recht des Menschen: Einführung in die evangelische Sozialethik (1978). An important collection (with contributions by Claus Westermann, Ulrich Luck, Martin Brecht and Jörg Baur) is J Baur (ed) Zum Thema Menschenrechte: theologische Versuche und Entwürfe (1977). For a recent collection of essays on the theological reflection on human rights, see for instance L Gearon Human Rights & Religion: A Reader (2002). This reader includes a valu- able introduction by Gearon and offers various positions on the relationship between religion (including different religions) and international human rights, with case studies from various regions throughout the world. The point of the reader is to show not only how human rights discourses contribute to individuals’ and groups’ rights to religious freedom, but also to demonstrate how different religions view the importance of human rights as such. Included is also a contribution by the South African theologian C Villa-Vicencio ‘Theology and Human Rights’ in L Gearon (ed) Human Rights & Religion (2002) at 98-119, where he specifically attempts to bridge the historical divide between individual and socio-economic rights via theol- ogy and the central theological affirmation of the worth and dignity of being human. In the closing essay (C Wellman ‘The Proliferation of Rights: Moral Progress or Empty Rhetoric?’ in L Gearon (ed) Human Rights & Religion (2002) at 368-388) the complex and, perhaps, troubled relationship between first, sec- ond and third generation rights is discussed. Apart from Villa-Vicencio’s work, another South African ethi- cist who contributed to human rights debates over many years is Danie du Toit; see D du Toit (ed) Menseregte: Opstelle (1984); D du Toit Die Mens en sy Regte: Geloof en Praktyk in Suid-Afrika (1988). 2 3 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E developed historically as a direct product of the Christian tradition, or that human rights rep- resent a universal value system that other traditions and cultures must merely accept in its pres- ent form. It is simply the modest claim that in their complex and controversial inter-relation- ships and in their openness for continuous improvement and criticism, contemporary human rights provide ‘perspectives of a human world’,26 with very strong analogies to central convic- tions of the Christian faith. This is also true of South Africa, and part of the reasons why churches and the local ecumenical church enthusiastically claim the Constitution and the Bill of Rights, and often eagerly monitor real or potential human rights violations. This is in fact the reason why churches could be expected to show a particular interest in implementing the so- called social and economic rights, whether as already formulated in the Constitution, or per- haps in even stronger form as well. It would therefore – at least from this theological perspective – be totally consistent with the faith, confession and theology of the Christian church if the South African ecumenical church, denominations and congregations, including church leaders and individual believers, would show very strong commitment to support the increased implementation of these social and economic rights, and would be very concerned with slow social transformation and delivery. To the extent that the South African church – understood in this comprehensive way – is not eagerly involved in supporting such implementation and does not contribute to the formation of public opinion and thereby practical policies in this direction, this would indeed be inconsistent with the faith, confession and theology of the church, and would raise the question of ‘theoretical drag’. III ‘Theoretical Drag’ Theoretical drag may be partly responsible for slow implementation of social and economic jus- tice in different ways and for different reasons. Popularly speaking, at least two major ways may be distinguished. On the one hand, the embodiment of social and economic justice in the form of laws and policies may be slow to follow public expectation and opinion. This happens for very understandable reasons. One of the strengths of modern legal systems is their reliability. The law is slow to change because it is intended to serve security of expectations, Rechtssicherheit.27 What is legal today should not be illegal tomorrow. The law can therefore not be changed arbitrarily, but tends to be conservative. Accordingly, laws carry the imprints of their origins and history, and they are often slow to respond to new challenges and problems, creating a certain ‘time-lag’. …Das durch die moralischen Vorstellungen, Herrschaftsformen und Macht- verhältnisse seiner Entstehungszeit geformte Recht gilt aber oft für lange Zeit; seine Beständigkeit soll ja gerade Verläßlichkeit und Rechtssicherheit verbürgen. Gegenüber neuen Problemlagen ist das Recht deshalb oft ungleichzeitig; wenn neue 26 See for example the very helpful systematic reflections of W Huber and HE Tödt Menschenrechte: Perspektiven einer menschlichen Welt (note 22 above) written by two Lutheran ethicists, but without doubt still one of the most valuable theological contributions in the field. 27 See N Luhmann Ausdifferenzierung des Rechts (note 3 above); M Welker ‘Security of expectations’ (1986) 66 Journal of Religion 237-260. Michael Welker, a Reformed systematic theological from Heidelberg and one of the most respected voices in postmodern theology, made extensive use of Luhmann’s complex theo- ries on modern societies in his earlier work and combined that in very insightful ways with Old and New Testament perspectives on justice, law and morality. Lebensverhältnisse entstehen, wenn neue moralische Vorstellungen sich durchsetzen, wenn tradierte Herrschaftsformen und Machtverhältnisse in Frage gestellt werden, zeigt sich oft ein ‘time-lag’ des Rechts. Seine konservativer Charakter mindert seine Steuerungs- und Orientierungsleistung. Es wirkt lähmend, ja vielleicht sogar lebens- feindlich… .28 On the other hand, the embodiment of social and economic justice in the form of laws and poli- cies may be slow because public expectation and opinion is not yet ready for it. Again, this may happen for very understandable reasons. Another strength of modern legal systems is precisely its independence from any specific moral or ethical viewpoint. That is indeed the important ele- ment of truth in positivist theories of justice. The legal system in a pluralist society, like South Africa, should not be moralised or ideologically misused by any particular tradition or com- munity, but should rather enable diverse moral and religious traditions and communities to co- exist peacefully and fairly. These two seemingly opposing processes may therefore take place simultaneously in a specific society. The implementation of social and economic rights may be slow since it does not (yet) reflect the expectations of specific (also moral and religious) com- munities and traditions in society, and it may be slow since it (still) reflects the opinion of per- haps the majority of (also moral and religious) communities and traditions in the same society. Empirical research by others will have to ascertain and document whether these processes are indeed at work in South Africa today. To the extent that these time-lags are indeed present in the implementation of social and economic justice in South Africa, this kind of ecumenical (and Reformed) theology will certainly be deeply concerned. This theological perspective supports those theoretical positions that argue that human rights are not only implemented by legal means and therefore also argue against all those restrictive views which claim that only individual rights should be regarded as proper rights, since only they are presumably justifiable and enforceable. Rather, this theological viewpoint would claim that human rights are promoted, implemented and realised, firstly, by political means, secondly by legal means and thirdly by resistance.29 Accordingly, the political and social preconditions must also be created without which human rights could not be enjoyed, including many of the rights formulated in sections of the South African Constitution’s Bill of Rights under environment (24), property (25, for example on land reform), housing (26), health care, food, water and social secu- rity (27) children (28), education (29), language, culture, religion and life in community (30 and 31). From this theological perspective, the state indeed has the responsibility to respect and pro- tect, but also ‘to promote and fulfil’ these rights (Chapter 2, section 7(2), Constitution). Necessary social and economic measures must be implemented and initiatives in the formation of public opinion that prepare, claim and welcome such measures should be supported and strengthened. Under specific circumstances, theology may be concerned with all three ways of imple- menting human rights, including social and economic rights. Theology can, therefore, sup- port victims of violations seeking legal remedies, especially when other social institutions fail to act (the second means). Theology can, also, join others in forms of public resistance whenever human dignity is systematically violated (the third means). The recent South African history bears witness to both these forms of theological involvement. The ecumeni- Theological Perspective on Theoretical Paradigms 235 28 W Huber Gerechtigkeit und Recht (note 22 above) at 59. 29 For an authoritative discussion of the integral role of protest and resistance within the Protestant theology and tradition, see W Huber Protestantismus und Protest (note 22 above); see also W Huber Gerechtigkeit und Recht (note 22 above) at 400-419. 2 3 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E cal church has been deeply involved, both in helping victims of human rights violations, also by seeking legal support, as well as in civil disobedience (regarding specific laws seen as unjust) and public resistance of the apartheid system as such.30 Under normal circum- stances, however, theology is particularly concerned with the first means of implementation, namely the political – creating the political conditions, strengthening the political will, find- ing concrete political policies and decisions and supporting practical political measures and actions that will help to implement human rights. Through the formation of public opinion, political action that will provide the conditions necessary for freedom and for living lives of human dignity is made possible.31 Theology does this – contributing to the formation of public opinion – primarily by serving the church.32 The ideal of theology and theologians directly impacting on society and public opinion is an illusion, at least in contemporary South Africa.33 The church, however, is a com- plex institution, with many forms and activities, and with the ability to influence South African 30 During the time of apartheid, for instance, the ecumenical church in South Africa through the South African Council of Churches and the Southern African Catholic Bishops’ Conference made various studies and took part in many actions to address, challenge and overcome the human rights abuses in the country. See for example B Johanson (ed) Human Rights in South Africa (1974); as well as Human Rights and Repression in Southern Africa: The Apartheid Machine Grinds On (1989). 31 The Scottish ecumenical theologian Duncan Forrester has worked extensively on the subject of justice and public theology. For his views on the insights that Christian theology can provide for contemporary theo- ries of justice, see D Forrester Christian Justice and Public Policy (1997). Another very insightful essay on the origin and meaning of the term ‘public theology’ may be found in EH Breitenberg ‘To Tell the Truth: Will the Real Public Theology Please Stand Up?’ (2003) 23 Journal of the Society of Christian Ethics 55- 96. Breitenberg distinguishes public theology from civil religion (out of which it partially developed), polit- ical theology, public church, public philosophy and public (or social) ethics. Another important and chal- lenging study on the role of the church in public life is by the renowned social ethicist LL Rasmussen Moral Fragments and Moral Community: A Proposal for Church in Society (1993). Also in the context of South Africa, this debate may be followed with the valuable book by K Clements Learning to Speak: The Church’s Voice in Public Affairs (1995), as well as contributions by NN Koopman ‘Some Comments on Public Theology Today’ (2003) 117 Journal of Theology for Southern Africa 3-19, and KT August The Quest for Being Public Church (2003) DTh thesis, University of Stellenbosch, Stellenbosch. 32 In this regard the relationship between church and ethics becomes important, as has been acknowledged in much recent debate in the ecumenical movement. An important study by the World Council of Churches on ecclesiology and ethics ‘sought to explore the link between what the church is and what the church does. It explored the ethical dimension not as a separate “department” of the church’s life, but as integrally relat- ed to its worship, its confession of faith, its witness and service in the world’ (TF Best and M Robra ‘Introduction’ in TF Best and M Robra (eds) Ecclesiology and Ethics: Ecumenical Engagement, Moral Formation and The Nature of the Church (1997) at vii). On the many publications that have appeared on this important debate, see especially the work of the systematic theologian LS Mudge The Church as Moral Community: Ecclesiology and Ethics in Ecumenical Debate (1998), and the ethicist R Hütter Evangelische Ethik als kirchliches Zeugnis: Interpretationen zu Schlüsselfragen theologischer Ethik in der Gegenwart (1993). For a survey of the vast amount of work that the World Council of Churches has done on the church’s responsibility to be a moral community (that not only reflects on its ethical dimension but also par- takes in the search for justice in the world), see the influential study TF Best and M Robra (eds) Ecclesiology and Ethics: Ecumenical Engagement, Moral Formation and The Nature of the Church (1997). This work deals with the three groundbreaking documents, ‘Costly Unity’ (1993), ‘Costly Commitment’ (1994) and ‘Costly Obedience’ (1996) which paved the way towards a new approach to the relationship between eccle- siology and ethics, as well as further contributions by Duncan Forrester and Larry Rasmussen, already referred to in the previous note. 33 In South African scholarly circles the impact of theology on society and public opinion has often been dis- cussed; see for example BC Lategan ‘Taking the Third Public Seriously’ in JW de Gruchy and S Martin (eds) Religion and the Reconstruction of Civil Society (1995) at 217-230; DJ Smit ‘Oor die Kerk as ‘n Unieke Samelewingsverband’ (1996) 36 Tydskrif vir Geesteswetenskappe 119-129; DJ Smit ‘Oor die Unieke society in important ways.34 It may, therefore, indeed and in several practical ways contribute towards changing the dominant theoretical paradigm – which, in the form of present public opinion, is probably contributing to resist the implementation of social and economic justice, according to the hypotheses of this project. So-called public theology and the public church participate in the formation of public opinion – with all its practical consequences also for the implementation of social and eco- nomic justice. It does this in the full awareness of being only voices amongst many other voices, and without any special claims. Public theology includes social ethics, as well as the specialised so-called ethics of social institutions or different spheres of life in modern soci- eties.35 Public theology through the public church has different modes of discourse as well as a wide range of activities at its disposal. These modes of discourse include the wisdom discourses of research, study, dialogue, consultation and education. It includes the priestly discourses of service and engagement, for example breaking down hostility and helping to build trust and reconciliation.36 It also includes – according to many, but not all – prophet- ic discourses such as critical witness and advocacy, when judged necessary.37 The activities Theological Perspective on Theoretical Paradigms 237 Openbare Rol van die Kerk’ (1996) 36 Tydskrif vir Geesteswetenskappe 190-204; DJ Smit ‘Openbare Getuienis en Publieke Teologie Vandag?’ (2003) 82 Scriptura 39-48. 34 For more detailed analyses of the church’s impact on South African society, see for example DJ Smit ‘The Impact of the Church in South Africa after the Collapse of the Apartheid Regime’ in K Bediako et al (eds) A New Day Dawning: African Christians Living the Gospel (2004) at 128-149; DJ Smit ‘Oor die Kerk en Maatskaplike Uitdagings in Ons Land’ (2004) 45 Nederduitse Gereformeerde Teologiese Tydskrif 350-362. In the last article for example it is argued that the church takes on at least six different social forms, name- ly: the worshiping assembly; the local congregation as human community; denominational structures and institutions; diverse local, regional and national ecumenical forms; individual believers in the fullness of their life and activity; participation of believers in different organisations, initiatives and forms of civil soci- ety. It is argued that each of these forms potentially impacts on society. 35 For essays dealing from different perspectives with the complex ways of building a human rights culture, see the volume of conference papers Botman and Sporre (eds) Building a Human Rights Culture (note 20 above). 36 A very instructive recent study on practices of social reconciliation, including consideration of the potential contribution of religious communities, is available in SF du Toit Learning to Live Together: Practices of Social Reconciliation (2003). 37 The respected social ethicist James Gustafson, formerly from the University of Chicago, gave a lecture series in 1987-88 on four such modes of moral discourse, which was subsequently published as J Gustafson Varieties of Moral Discourse: Prophetic, Narrative, Ethical, and Policy (1988). The first form of moral dis- course, namely prophetic discourse, seeks to identify a moral evil in society and to raise awareness of the particular issue. It uses passionate language to criticise and confront existing power structures and offers ideal alternatives to the state of affairs. Narrative discourse tells paradigmatic stories that may reveal overt or hidden morals. Narrative tries, in a more subtle way than prophetic discourse, to persuade and inspire people and communities. On their own these two forms are, however, not sufficient. Moral discourse requires policy discourse, which rather asks what actions and transformation would in fact be possible (rather than simply desirable) within the given circumstances. Finally it also requires technical, ethical dis- course in the strict sense, which tries to analyse and clarify matters through conceptual distinctions. Gustafson’s typology initially remained limited to the ecumenical sphere (where it in fact originated after he made a thorough study of the ethical documentation of the World Council of Churches), but recently it has been taken up in the wider field of Christian ethics, such as the recent book by BV Brady The Moral Bond of Community: Justice and Discourse in Christian Morality (1998). This has also been introduced in South African Christian ethical circles – see for example DJ Smit and De Villiers ‘Hoe Christene in Suid-Afrika by Mekaar Verby Praat ... Oor Vier Morele Spreekwyses in die Suid-Afrikaanse Kerklike Konteks’ (1994) 15 Skrif en Kerk 228-247. 2 3 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E of the public church range from the worship of local congregations38 through the institu- tional work of denominations and ecumenical bodies to the initiatives of believers and vol- untary initiatives. The Beyers Naudé Center for Public Theology is dedicated to serve these purposes through such research, education and involvement, thereby hopefully contributing to more social and economic justice in South Africa today.39 38 For a discussion of the both constructive and destructive ways that Christian worship can contribute to social justice, see DJ Smit ‘On Learning to See’ in; DJ Smit ‘’Seeing Things Differently’ - On Prayer and Politics’ in L Holness and RK Wüstenberg (eds) Theology in Dialogue: The Impact of the Arts, Humanities, and Science on Contemporary Religious Thought: Essays in Honor of John W de Gruchy (2002) at 271- 284. 39 The Beyers Naude Centre for Public Theology is one of a growing number of public theology institutes in the ecumenical church (www.sun.ac.za/theology/bnc). Others may be found in Scotland (The Centre for Theology and Public Issues at the University of Edinburgh, http://www.div.ed.ac.uk/theologypubl.html), the United States (The Abraham Kuyper Center for Public Theology at Princeton Theological Seminary, http://www.ptsem.edu/grow/kuyper/; The Center for Business, Religion and Public Life at Pittsburgh Theological Seminary, http://www.pts.edu/busrel.html) and elsewhere. Beyond Labour Law’s Parochialism: A Re-envisioning of the Discourse of Redistribution* L U C Y A W I L L I A M S Professor of Law, Northeastern University School of Law, Boston I Introduction Left labour and welfare law constitute two primary fields of discourse about redistribution. However, each has traditionally seen itself as isolated, not only from one another but also from the critically related fields of immigration, family, and international law. The failure of each to engage with the other results in theoretical and political gaps that have contributed to both fields’ inability to envision redistribution strategies sufficient to measure up to the power and pervasiveness of the conservative/neo-liberal agenda. This essay seeks to draw threads between fields of inquiry and practice that progressives, especially labour and welfare lawyers, must understand as intimately linked. I argue that any progressive transformation of labour law requires intense engagement with welfare law. With notable exceptions, labour law still largely situates questions of power and income distribution within the framework of labour markets. Its perspective on work remains limited to wage labour. And it still privileges collective bargaining by unions within a nation-state as the pri- mary site of progressive initiatives for economic and social redistribution. These internalized ways of thinking guarantee that labour law will become increasingly stultified and marginal- ized as the new century progresses, and that labour lawyers will have steadily less to contribute to economic redistribution and social change. Likewise, progressive welfare lawyers have traditionally focused almost exclusively on cen- tral government transfers as the redistributive hub, failing to engage with and expose the state’s role in constructing labour markets. More recently, since the 1996 US ‘welfare reform’, dis- cussed below, progressive welfare lawyers have often focused on developing social services to help poor families ‘overcome barriers to employment,’ instead of challenging the structure of low-wage labour markets. Activists in both welfare and labour law, viewing their constituen- cies within nation-state boundaries, have not infrequently voiced protectionist rhetoric. Privileging nation-state waged work as the site for redistributional politics ignores and deval- ues the needs and concerns of millions of productive, low- and non-waged workers in the glob- alized economy. Likewise privileging government transfers as the primary site of redistribution, * This paper was originally published in J Conaghan, RM Fischl & K Klare (eds) Labour Law in an Era of Globalization: Transformative Practices and Possibilities (2002) at 93-114 and is reprinted here with kind permission of L Williams, J Conaghan, RM Fischl and K Klare and Oxford University Press. 2 4 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E counterintuitive as this might sound, contributes to the dominant discourse of a ‘free market’ by failing to expose the politically chosen, legally constructed labour market structures that reinforce income disparity. Left lawyers certainly do not intend their theoretical formulations and political stances to render disempowered populations invisible. But often, through lack of interdisciplinary and cross-border dialogue, we fail effectively to criticize our own positions and re-imagine broad-based redistributive political agendas. This chapter attempts to expose ways in which many left labour and welfare lawyers have unwittingly played into a discourse that reinforces the economic status quo by validating the economic structures creating poverty. The left’s default can be seen particularly in a failure fully to appreciate and expose the reinforcing links between three seemingly disparate legal-theoret- ic discourses that feed into the dominant political consensus on social policy. Together these dis- courses privilege and naturalize waged labour within a free market as the arena for productive participation in society, thereby justifying the assault on the welfare state. The first is the discourse of the public and private distinction. Mainstream legal thought, both conservative and liberal, conceives private law as arising more or less naturally, rather than being a contingent product of state policy. Within this understanding, private law, and the institutions it structures such as market and family, arise ‘prior to’ and independent of state power. This conceptual framework naturalizes the existing distribution of wealth and power in these social arenas, which then appear to have nothing to do with, and indeed, to require pro- tection from state intervention. In addition, it necessarily marginalizes welfare law and policy by portraying it as government ‘intervention’ into natural market outcomes and family arrange- ments. When welfare lawyers focus on government transfers, and when labour lawyers mar- ginalize welfare law as state intervention, both are contributing to the legitimization of the ‘free market.’ Similarly central within the dominant legal and policy framework, is the conception of a ‘worker’ as someone engaged in wage labour. Social protection laws connected to waged work frequently further narrow the meaning of ‘worker’ to those in full-time, high-wage, long-term jobs. This definition identifies as ‘non-workers’ and therefore excludes many individuals who are, in fact, active in waged work as well as the many who work but do not receive a wage. These definitions reinforce the socially constructed identities upon which mainstream discourse and political rhetoric are founded. By pursuing a traditional social welfare agenda1 primarily connected to an anachronistic image of the waged worker, and by distancing other members of society as ‘non-productive,’ labour contributes to the stigmatization of millions of low-waged and non-waged workers, including welfare recipients and immigrants. Finally, there is the notion of social citizenship, to which some progressive welfare and labour policy-makers have subscribed, often as a repository of democratic and egalitarian aspirations, without critically assessing the gender, racial, and economic biases of traditional citizenship dis- course. In addition, they typically view their fields within the boundaries of nation-state citi- zenship, without engaging with the current social reality of global economic integration or the 1 In the US, ‘welfare’ is commonly used to refer to Aid to Families with Dependent Children (AFDC), replaced in 1996 by Temporary Assistance to Needy Families (TANF). Throughout this chapter, I use the term ‘wel- fare’ to refer to social assistance programmes, the eligibility for which is means-tested, not conditioned on a requisite tie to waged work. I use the term ‘social welfare’ in a broader sense, to include both social assis- tance and social insurance programmes, in which eligibility is defined by a sufficient attachment to waged work. class, racial, and alienage implications of a citizenship paradigm that fails to incorporate a cross-border perspective. By failing critically to analyse our roles in perpetuating these discourses, left labour and wel- fare theoreticians have, albeit inadvertently, ceded discursive and political ground to the con- servative/neo-liberal consensus, contributing by default to the hegemonic discourses that por- tray the social status quo as natural. Through interdisciplinary and cross-national dialogue by and among progressives working in the fields of labour, welfare, immigration, and internation- al economic organization, we can strengthen our critiques, and better position ourselves to dis- rupt the ‘naturalness’ and self-fulfilling quality of dominant discourse. My particular focus is on the perceived lack of connection between labour and welfare law, primarily in a US and UK context. I then draw threads from labour and welfare to the areas of family, immigration, and international economic law. My hope is that by elucidating theoreti- cal and political gaps in and among these fields, we can develop a more sophisticated redis- tributive agenda – one that is multicultural and gender-sensitive, allowing, indeed encouraging, transformation of social roles, and one that incorporates a re-imagined, globalized conception of citizenship, attentive to racial and gender differences. Finally, it should be one that reclaims and re-legitimates redistribution, moving beyond the mere redistribution of income to facilitate the redistribution of power, resulting in self-actualization and active citizenship within the mar- ket, family, and political community. One (although only one) step toward developing the the- oretical tools needed to revitalize transformative politics is for labour lawyers and others thor- oughly to engage with the insights and innovations of modern welfare law. II The Legal Creation of Poverty Welfare law is premised upon and uniquely illuminates fundamental teachings of critical legal thought first developed, in the US, by the Legal Realists. The core insight is that all legal rules are contingent products of human choice that have distributive consequences. That is, legal rules affect the distribution of wealth and power, whether vertically among classes, horizontal- ly among races and genders, or internationally among regions, communities, and nation-states. For a century, traditional legal thinkers have engaged in intense ideological work to suppress or marginalize these insights. Left-legal theorists and practitioners have resisted this hegemonic view. But they have never fully appreciated the theoretical contributions of welfare law or its potential as a forum to expose the legal means by which poverty is perpetuated. By uncritical- ly accepting the mainstream view that welfare law takes market outcomes as its starting point, left-legal theory has implicitly validated the mainstream view that the background rules struc- turing market behaviour are not really acts of government. The dominant political discourse in Western nations, reinforced by our legal culture, teach- es that poverty arises naturally and that the legal system bears no responsibility for causing it. Private law concepts of family, tort, property, and freedom of contract are made to appear as the necessary and neutral framework of social and economic power relations, arising inde- pendently of law. The dominant political culture denies that these background rules privilege any group or have anything to do with allocating wealth or income. The role of law in distrib- uting property, valuing waged labour, and consequently devaluing family work, is almost always invisible. In fact, the stubborn persistence of poverty, in both developed and developing countries, largely results from political and legal decisions and institutions that generate and sustain a Re-Envisioning the Discourse of Redistribution 241 2 4 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E sharply unequal distribution of wealth and resources. Far from being natural or neutral, legal rules, norms, and practices play a central part in maintaining poverty by according privilege to and legitimating certain values, interests, and concerns over others. Legal precepts shape social roles by assigning power and responsibility in social relationships, whether within the family or in the workplace. For example, the everyday common sense of modern, democratic, political and legal cultures – that the family is a private haven from the public realms of market and government – ignores the intimate, indispensable, and legally constructed connections between these social spheres. As dis- cussed below, the production of goods and services for the market by paid workers depends on the subsidy of unpaid care-givers’ – predominantly women’s – labour. Similarly, family wealth and income could not exist without the full range of property rules entrenched by government. The rules that comprise freedom of contract, referring to rich and poor, male and female, and employ- er and employee as ‘equals’ because they formally share the power to contract, ratify steeply unequal access by individuals and families to the economic means of life-enjoyment. The state is not independent from other social structures. The state entrenches those structures. Nor is the existing array of background legal rules inevitable. Human actors, making implic- it or explicit moral and political decisions about who is and is not deserving of reward, create legal entitlements that reflect and enact distinct political values. All of the ways in which soci- ety sustains income inequality and poverty – whether through government programmes fund- ed by general taxation, market structures, familial responsibility, or private charity – reflect politically chosen regulatory policies. Welfare law, whose raison d’être is to question the existing distribution of wealth and in- come, provides a forum for exploding the neutrality of these background rules of entitlement. It is, therefore, at least potentially, a permanent threat within mainstream jurisprudence because it reveals the false pretense or illusion that the bedrock common law of property, market, and family is distributionally neutral and exists prior to and independent of governmental action. From a critical perspective, welfare discourse sees every legal artifact as crafted by officials in a given historical and institutional framework. Thus, welfare law persistently threatens to reveal the contingency and political character of all law. Mainstream politicians, at least subliminally alert to the Trojan-horse nature of welfare law and its potential to explode the most basic assumptions of the legal culture, periodically go to considerable lengths to suppress its critical aspect and to recast welfare law in a manner con- sistent with status quo assumptions. Just as labour law’s potentially radical implications for wealth and power distribution, even within the limited waged work sphere, were blunted by a functional reinterpretation of the discourse,2 so, too, have progressive ideas in welfare law needed to be domesticated or marginalized. Thus, mainstream policymakers and jurists face the intellectual challenge of creating a conception of welfare law that, while moderately re-distrib- utive, does not disrupt or delegitimate core institutions. To accomplish this goal, a modicum of procedural due process, and thus a perception of fun- damental fairness, was incorporated into welfare law.3 But this concession, important as it was, has been ultimately overwhelmed in significance by increasingly vitriolic debate about the wel- fare system’s very purpose. The normative foundations of welfare state theory are ideas about 2 K E Klare ‘Workplace Democracy and Market Reconstruction: An Agenda for Legal Reform’(1988) 38 Catholic University L Rev at 1, ‘Judicial Deradicalization of the Wagner Act and the Origins of Modern Legal Consciousness’ (1978) 62 Minnesota LR at 1049. 3 See, eg, Goldberg v Kelly 397 US 254 (1970) and its progeny. equality and minimum material circumstances for a meaningful life-experience. Over the last twenty years, the ‘new’ welfare theory, legitimated and promoted by a policy consensus of con- servatives (for example, Thatcher and Reagan) and liberal/neo-liberals (for example, Blair and Clinton), has promoted different assumptions and commitments. One normative baseline of this strange alliance is a modernized version of the old ideal of liberty, meaning freedom from governmental interference. Advancing under the banner of the so-called ‘Washington Consensus’ and espousing the virtues of deregulation, limited govern- ment spending, and free trade, politicians in many Western nations4 have attacked and dis- mantled previously well-established welfare programmes. Most varieties of the neo-liberal tra- dition take the position that social provision is a sometime necessary evil to correct market fail- ures and imperfections, just as sometimes the state must ‘intervene’ in domestic matters because of family-breakdown.5 Many New Right theorists and politicians acknowledge the possibility of market failure in theory but doubt its existence in practice. Accordingly, social provision for them is simply an interference with the free market and has no legitimate purpose. But the var- ious wings coalesce around so-called free markets and the two-parent heterosexual family as the appropriate institutions for distributing wealth and power. In sum, the intellectual achievement (if one can call it that) of the conservative/neo-liberal ‘welfare reform’ consensus is to formulate social policy as an adjunct to private law. Questions of income, wealth, and power inequality – let alone redistribution – fade from the picture. Moreover, the consensus is also built on historical ambivalence over how much the poor are responsible for their own plight, resurfacing the causation issue with intensely pejorative rhet- oric. Welfare benefits, the consensus holds, generate pernicious social consequences, as well as inefficiencies, and must be eliminated because they foster a culture among the poor that does not reflect majoritarian values.6 This discourse attributes poverty to individual fault, charac- terized as a lack of the work ethic in the first world and a lack of acquaintance with or mas- tery of entrepreneurial values and skills in developing countries. The common assumption is that individual agency can always overcome cultural, societal, and economic obstacles. The argument continues that these individual character flaws are largely created and sustained by the institution of welfare. Thus it is argued, without a trace of irony, that because the welfare state creates dependency, welfare actually causes poverty rather than ameliorating it. Without state intervention, the free market would create the incentives for mainstream attitudes and behaviour, by which is meant those consistent with waged work and the patriarchal family. The rhetoric of individual responsibility and institutional dependency legitimates the inevitability of Re-Envisioning the Discourse of Redistribution 243 4 Of course, many European countries continue to maintain more expansive welfare states, including addi- tional family supports, albeit still retaining elements of gender bias as well as racist connotations in terms of immigration law and immigrant access to benefits. The role of social protection and labour in many Latin American, African, and Asian countries is, in many ways, even more complex. This chapter does not attempt to highlight and problematize the labour and social welfare debate throughout the world, but focuses rather on US/UK discourse, which currently forms the basis of discussion in many other countries, in part because of World Bank and International Monetary Fund structural austerity measures. 5 FE Olsen ‘The Myth of State Intervention in the Family’ (1985) 18 University of Michigan J of Law Reform 835 at 835. 6 For discussions of the history of welfare theory from various sub-movements of the right, see L Williams ‘Welfare Law and Legal Entitlements: The Social Roots of Poverty’ in D Kairys (ed) The Politics of Law: A Progressive Critique (1998) 569; L Williams Decades of Distortion: The Right’s 30-Year Assault on Welfare (1997); L Williams ‘The Ideology of Division: Behavior Modification Welfare Reform Proposals’ (1992) 102 Yale L J 719. 2 4 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E growing disparity in the distribution of wealth both within and between nation-states and underwrites the policy imperative of dismantling the welfare state. The hegemonic success of this rhetoric has led to a significant retrenchment in availability of and entitlement to social pro- tection benefits. Despite differences, mainstream political rhetoric about welfare, from moderate-liberal to the far right, have come to share a common thread in recent decades by subsuming welfare pol- icy into private law. At best, welfare smooths out rough edges of the free market (what are tech- nically called ‘market imperfections’ or ‘externalities’). This theoretical ploy cried out for a pro- gressive response aimed to show that the background rules and assumptions by which law reg- ulates the free market themselves constitute a site of distributive conflict. Instead, most left-legal criticism has pursued one of two alternative avenues. Progressive welfare theorists have largely seen their task as that of defending the legitimacy of state ‘intervention’ to achieve egalitarian redistribution. Of course, they make strong argu- ments against welfare retrenchment, for example, skillfully rebutting the argument that welfare is an addictive drug, and exposing the racism and sexism inherent in the welfare reform con- sensus. But their ultimate solution to poverty and inequality is still framed as a system of cen- tral government transfer payments, criticized by some politicians as a ‘tax and spend mentali- ty.’ The Achilles heel of this approach is that it concedes the mainstream’s central premises, that free markets and governmental regulation are diametrically opposed modes of social ordering, and that family and markets are autonomous from state power. Progressive welfare advocates’ method of redistribution assumes a conceptual framework in which a ‘regulatory’ state inter- venes in a ‘free market.’ That focus contributes to the belief that the legal background rules gov- erning the market and the family have no part in the distribution of income and power and operate in a totally separate realm from welfare law. In other words, welfare law is about state intervention in a normally ‘free’ realm, while background legal rules arise more or less sponta- neously in private spheres. Thus welfare law’s traditional, bounded assumption that central government transfer policy is the primary arena of redistribution has frustrated its efforts to counter the centre/right consensus and challenge the overall legal structure of inequality. While labour lawyers take for granted that labour markets are sites of distributive conflict, they customarily fixate on increasing waged workers’ bargaining power. Unable to think very far beyond labour market conflict as the engine of redistribution, left labour academics and activists have unwittingly reinforced the naturalization of family, contract, property, and tort law. Rarely do they deploy their critical arsenal against the background rules of private law that give existing labour markets their highly inegalitarian shape. Like most practitioners and legal academics, they fail to appreciate the importance and theoretical richness of welfare law or to develop its connections with and implications for labour law. By marginalizing welfare law as separate from labour law, they have contributed to a discourse that frames welfare law as com- prising isolated acts of ‘state regulation,’ thereby naturalizing the free market. This limited view of welfare law as anomalous state intervention, and the artificial concep- tual divisions between family, state, and market,7 regrettably mirrors the ideas behind the cur- rent welfare reform consensus. The hegemonic rhetoric, in both the US and UK, deflects atten- tion from the political underpinnings of income inequality and instead focuses on an alleged 7 See generally AS Orloff ‘Gender and the Social Rights of Citizenship: The Comparative Analysis of Gender Relations and Welfare States’ (1993) 58 American Sociological Rev 303. breakdown of the natural family and the failure of poor people, particularly lone mothers, to participate in the ‘free’ market. The prevailing political consensus relies on this unchallenged belief in the neutrality of private law to support the dismantling of welfare programmes, artic- ulated as public interventions in the natural order but which are really ameliorative adjuncts to alienated waged work. Critical welfare and labour law must expose the state’s presence in struc- turing and distributing power in families and markets, and it must reclaim welfare law as a site of redistributional politics. It must engage with and undermine the central premise of the con- temporary welfare reform consensus (and its historical antecedents) that poverty can be allevi- ated simply by strengthening families and pushing people into wage labour. And it must expose and challenge the class, gender, and racial biases of the legal rules structuring family life and market processes. III Social Welfare Laws Construct Identities and Exclusions Having artificially distinguished public and private realms, placing welfare in the former, the next challenge for mainstream political discourse was to explain why some central government income transfers are legitimate without exposing the contingency of all socio-economic struc- tures. Why choose some income transfers and not others, just as easy to imagine (for example, a guaranteed minimum income funded by steeply progressive taxation)? One solution has been to define ‘legitimate’ income transfers so as to reinforce the core institutions and understand- ings of the social status quo, made ‘natural’ by common law background rules. Thus, social welfare laws and policies were crafted in the shadow of an assumed model of alienated wage labour, comprised of breadwinners who were subsidized by unpaid work in the home based on a gendered division of labour. In the process, social welfare law built upon and added its own nuances to law’s naturalizing and legitimation projects. An area of doctrine that illuminates this process concerns the legal designation of eligible claimants for various social welfare programmes. In legal fiction, drafters of social welfare statutes develop policy based on a population consisting of people with fixed identities inde- pendent of law (for example, a person who is, in medical terms, permanently disabled from waged work). But drafting and administering welfare laws are political practices with discur- sive as well as instrumental consequences. In short, legal work creates meanings. Social welfare- related legal practices partially construct the identities of deserving and undeserving claimants. By way of illustration, one of the most fundamental distinctions in social welfare law is between programmes for ‘workers’ who suffer income interruption (due, for example, to unem- ployment, accident, or retirement) and programmes for ‘non-workers.’ Social insurance pro- grammes for ‘workers’ or ex-workers are typically financed by employer-employee contribution schemes. Social assistance programmes for ‘non-workers’ are commonly financed from general revenues, and are less generous and highly stigmatized. An elaborate body of statutory rules and doctrines determines who is a ‘worker’ and who is not. The worker versus non-worker distinction is highly ideological. It draws upon and develops the messages of the legal culture generally – the public/private distinction, the disjuncture of family and market, and the privileging of market activity. The highly negative popular image of welfare beneficiaries is largely a self-fulfilling prophecy of general social welfare law and poli- cy, built upon long-standing prejudice against the poor, whether in waged or non-waged work. To begin with, the fundamental, and fundamentally gendered, assumption of mainstream theory is that ‘work’ means paid work, and ‘worker’ means someone who works almost exclu- Re-Envisioning the Discourse of Redistribution 245 2 4 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E sively in wage labour. Traditional theories of ‘productivity’ largely exclude the value of unpaid labour as an integral factor, a cost of production. Workplace productivity assessments are based on factors that isolate one’s role in paid work and ignore other parts of life that influ- ence, contribute to, or detract from productivity. While economists and lawyers speculate about increased ‘efficiency’ or ‘productivity’ as if these were fixed or ‘natural’ concepts, they ignore production costs currently absorbed by the household, such as the provision of health care and childcare. The production of value outside and apart from paid work for employers does not ‘count’ (it is valuated at zero), so policy makers take this form of subsidy largely for granted.8 In addition, since everyone (including, by the twentieth century, women) owns his or her labour power and has freedom of contract, everyone potentially can work (that is, earn wages). So if a woman does not earn wages, and also fails to marry and make a home for a wage-earn- ing spouse, her poverty is attributable to her social deviancy. Such a person becomes ‘depend- ent’ on ‘the state.’ The main point of this rhetoric is, of course, to stigmatize the victim, but there are several powerful subtexts. First, since waged work is the opposite of non-waged work, and since non-waged work is ‘dependent,’ waged work must be ‘independent.’ Therefore main- stream theory complacently ignores or actively suppresses the alienated, subordinate, often authoritarian character of waged work, and most waged workers’ utter dependence on how well their employers manage and cope with technological and market shifts. Secondly, since ‘non-worker’ recipients of social assistance are dependent on the state, every- one else must be independent of the state. Therefore, mainstream theory ignores the role of gov- ernment in creating and protecting the ‘entitlement programmes’ of the well-to-do, namely, the background laws of property, contract, family, and tort, not to mention tax and other subsidies to business and to middle and upper-class households. The mainstream framing of social welfare policy in terms of the worker/non-worker dis- tinction produces many unfortunate consequences for both general public debate and the left’s ability to imagine transformative alternatives. Among the most damaging is that this perspective renders invisible the population who are both ‘workers’ (that is, waged workers) and ‘non-workers’ (welfare recipients, most of whom do massive amounts of unpaid family work). Large numbers of people cycle between low-waged work and welfare programmes. Studies within the US, immediately preceding the 1996 US ‘welfare reform’, document welfare and waged work as inextricably intertwined, thereby challenging the widely held assumption that welfare recipients are a category separate and distinct from paid workers. A majority of women receiving welfare move in and out of low-waged work on a regular basis.9 One study found that of the sixty-four per cent of women on welfare for the first time who left the rolls within two years, almost half left for work. But of those who left, three-quarters eventually returned; forty- 8 On the economic interdependence of paid and unpaid work and its invisibility in dominant discourse, see further K Rittich ‘Feminization and Contingency: Regulating the Stakes of work for Woman’ in J Conaghan, RM Fischl & K Klare (eds) Labour Law in an Era of Globalization: Transformative Practices and Possibilities (2002) 117-137. 9 If one used ‘point in time’ data, ie, counting the percentage of those on a given day both receiving welfare and participating in wage work, there appears to be very little overlap, figures showing only about 7% of welfare recipients are also in paid labour. Staff of House Committee on Ways and Means Background Material and Data on Programs. Within the Jurisdiction of the Committee on Ways and Means (1996) 104th Cong 2d Sess at 474. But this type of data collection does not take into account the ‘cyclical wel- fare/work population.’ five per cent returned within a year.10 Another study found that seventy per cent of welfare recipients participated in some way in the wage labour force over a two-year period: twenty per cent combined paid work and welfare, twenty-three per cent worked intermittently, receiving welfare between jobs, seven per cent worked limited hours and looked for more paid work, and twenty three per cent searched for, but could not obtain, paid work. The women in this study held an average of 1.7 paid jobs over the two-year period and spent an average of sixteen weeks looking for paid work.11 As in most Western nations, the US legal rules concerning eligibility for benefits under the Unemployment Insurance (UI) system reflect the false dichotomy between waged workers and welfare recipients. Although low-waged workers contribute to the UI benefit-pool in the sense that employers pass payroll taxes onto them in the form of lower wages, UI rules exclude many low- waged workers, particularly women12 and people of colour, from the definition of ‘employee.’13 Minimum past earning requirements in many states14 render ineligible many part-time, low-wage workers.15 Thus most of the single mothers who moved from welfare to wage labour and then lost their jobs found they were ineligible for the UI Program. In one study of women-maintained families in which the mother was employed for at least three months, almost three times as many families turned to welfare as to UI. In another study of 1,200 single mothers who received wel- fare for at least two months in a twenty-four month period, forty-three per cent also worked, aver- aging just about half-time. However, only eleven per cent of those who worked later qualified for UI. By denying many low-wage earning mothers transitional support when they become unem- ployed, forcing them to resort or return to welfare, UI law constructs them as persons who are ‘not attached to the labour force,’ that is, as social deviants who cause their own poverty by refus- ing to work and who are, therefore, unworthy of assistance from society. Re-Envisioning the Discourse of Redistribution 247 10 LD Pavetti The Dynamics of Welfare and Work: Exploring the Process by Which Young Women Work Their Way Off Welfare, unpublished PhD dissertation, JFK School of Government, Harvard University (1993). 11 R Spalter-Roth Making Work Pay: The Real Employment Opportunities of Single Mothers Participating in the AFDC Program (Washington DC: Institute for Women’s Policy Research, 1994). 12 20% of women were excluded based on minimum weeks of prior employment as opposed to eight percent of men. 10% of women were disqualified based on the required amount of earnings in the highest earning quarter compared to 4% of men. Minimum earnings requirements disqualified 4% of women as opposed to 2% of men. Taken together, prior earnings requirements excluded 34% of women as opposed to 15% of men. YH Yoon, R Spalter-Roth & M Baldwin Unemployment Insurance: Barriers to Access for Women and Part-Time Workers (Washington DC: National Commission for Employment Policy, 1995) 24. 13 For example, UI coverage requires not just a connection to waged work, but a sufficient connection, dis- advantaging low-waged and contingent workers. To meet monetary eligibility minimums, low-waged work- ers must work more hours than higher paid workers: Advisory Council on Unemployment Compensation, Report and Recommendations (Washington, DC: US Government Printing Office, 1995) 17. In nine states, a half-time, full-year (1040 hours of work) worker who earns minimum wage is completely ineligible for benefits, while the worker who earns $8.00 an hour for the same hours of work is eligible (ibid). Likewise, a two-day a week, full-year worker earning minimum wage would be ineligible in 29 states, but the same worker earning $8.00 an hour would be eligible in all but two states (ibid). 14 33 states require that a minimum amount of earnings be received in an individual’s high-waged quarter. Thus, workers who concentrate their work hours in a shorter period are more likely to meet the eligibility requirements (Advisory Council on Unemployment Compensation (note 13 above) at 94, 98). For exam- ple, nine states would disqualify a half-time, full-year minimum wage worker (who worked 1040 hours), but only one state would disqualify the same worker if she worked the same number of hours full-time for 26 weeks and did not work at all for the rest of the base period (ibid 98). 15 One study found that 10% of all unemployed part-time workers received unemployment insurance as opposed to 36% of full-time workers: Yoon et al (note 12 above) at 34. 2 4 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E Far from welfare recipients demonstrating an unwillingness to work, these studies suggest that most welfare recipients prefer and endeavor to earn wages even under the most trying per- sonal circumstances. Their efforts are frequently frustrated by barriers for which legal rules and public policies are responsible. Often, they cannot find employment for which they are quali- fied. Even in times of low unemployment, low-waged work conditions are so precarious as to guarantee that many low-waged earners will periodically cycle through periods of unemploy- ment. Low-waged jobs in the US, UK, and many other developed nations pay below-subsistence wages (thereby ensuring that workers cannot provide for their families), provide little or no training or advancement opportunities, and typically have inflexible work schedules allowing no adjustment for the family care needs of low-income families who do not have nannies or other family members available to care for their children and elders. Low-wage employers often induce employee turnover as a wage-depression strategy. Far from providing a forum for self- actualization, independence, autonomy, and empowerment, these jobs generate self-alienation, depression, poverty within wage work, and disempowerment. The perceived bifurcation of waged work and welfare receipt allows the idea of dependen- cy to be severed from any connection with the sale of labour power in the market, discursive- ly erasing the alienation and subordination within low-waged work. The legal system defines who is a worker and who is independent, thereby stigmatizing adults who do not meet the legal definition of worker as trapped in dependency. The legally constructed identity of wel- fare recipients as shiftless non-workers, rather than as ‘autonomous’ wage earners, reinforces the negative images of welfare recipients that resonate so deeply with much of the US and UK public. This ‘reality’ drives the debate about welfare reform, as, for example, during the US debates leading to the passage of the 1996 Personal Responsibility and Work Opportunity Reconciliation Act (PRWORA). The PRWORA limits a family’s ability to get welfare to a maximum of five years in a lifetime, and mandates stringent work requirements even during the eligibility period. In other words, the Orwellian power of legal discourse to portray work- ers as non-workers creates a disconnection between people’s experience as workers and their recognition as workers. Like the background rules that divide the family and the market into independent ‘private’ spheres, both separated from ‘state-imposed’ welfare, social welfare laws create and reinforce identities and images that deeply influence labour and welfare policy debates. Unfortunately, progressive labour lawyers have often played into this discourse, again privi- leging labour markets as the site for redistributive politics and wage labour as the arena of pro- ductivity. The dominant consensus treating ‘dependency’ as a condition located outside waged work helps sustain a cultural and psychological framework that encourages the labour move- ment and waged workers to deny or overlook their dependency and subordination. Labour movements can and do view government transfer programmes serving paid workers as legiti- mate entitlements for those who contribute to society, not for those dependent on society. For example, UI laws in the US often reflect hard fought victories for the labour movement. But traditionally, as US unions lobby for improvements in and expansion of UI laws, they have consciously distanced themselves from welfare recipients. Indeed, in urging UI reform, unions have often explicitly invoked the rhetoric of the ‘worthiness’ of UI as an earned entitlement, specifically juxtaposed against a view of welfare as an unearned ‘dole’ for non-workers. Perhaps they have done so under an assumption that union members or prospective members will never need to rely on welfare or be out of waged work for substantial periods of time because of fam- ily responsibilities, or that incremental victories for waged workers within the bargaining unit can only be achieved by valorizing a certain ‘self-reliant’ image of earner. However justified, this approach has deflected labour’s attention away from government social policy as an arena of redistributive politics separate from ameliorating market imperfections. Thus organized labour plays into the fundamentally conservative vision that even favoured social programmes like UI (as we have seen for welfare programmes as well) are simply an adjunct to market outcomes, rather than potentially redistributive programmes. And, however unwittingly, labour reinforces the social exclusion of non-waged workers. IV Who is a Citizen? Recently, activists and theorists on both the left and right have embraced a refurbished dis- course of citizenship as a paradigm for developing welfare policy. Despite some rhetorical appeal, this turn to citizenship discourse has not avoided, and, in some ways, has deepened, the problems arising from more traditional framings of social policy questions: privileging the mar- ket as a site for self-actualization and independence, while often ignoring, misunderstanding, and, on occasion, rendering invisible invidious class, gender, racial, and alienage biases, there- by devaluing subordinated social groups. Advocates of the New Right have advanced claims about the obligations of citizens to sup- port arguments for reducing or eliminating social protection programmes. They pose ‘active cit- izenship,’ by which they mean participation in waged work, as an alternative to social protec- tion. This rhetoric has been generously incorporated into current policy thinking in the US and UK and lends support to the welfare reform consensus. Ironically, many left activists and theo- rists in the US and UK are also embracing a discourse of citizenship, in part as a medium for developing arguments to defend social protection in the face of the welfare reform consensus. At times, they rely on an aspect of the idea of social citizenship,16 that communal provision of basic needs is critical to human flourishing and self-actualization. The democratic and republi- can overtones are appealing, and revitalizing the concept of social citizenship may be seen as a helpful way to move beyond the liberal conception of formal equality based on acquisition of property, the franchise, and the right to associate. On the other hand, the concept of citizenship carries considerable ideological baggage. The willingness of progressive activists and theorists to work within an unreconstituted, unchallenged discourse of citizenship can be dangerously misleading in two important ways: First, within most political and theoretical discourse to date, the idea of citizenship is premised on one or another version of the public/private distinction, with the obligations of cit- izenship, albeit couched in neutral terms, incorporating racial and gendered models of white male productivity in the public sphere. Secondly, classical concepts of citizenship rest on a model of political community that most theorists, including most left theorists, have been unwilling or unable to detach from the notion of the ‘nation-state.’ The modern nation-state is the product of historical forces, including conquest, imperialism, exclusion, and genocide. Nationalism is sometimes an emancipatory discourse of self-determination, but is often a plat- form for racism and domination. Thus the left should interrogate not valorize the nation-state or build a political theory on it. Re-Envisioning the Discourse of Redistribution 249 16 See generally TH Marshall ‘On Citizenship and Social Class’ in Class, Citizenship and Social Development (1964) at 28 where citizenship is defined as ‘a status bestowed on those who are full members of a com- munity’ and developing three stages of citizenship: civil, connoting liberty and property rights, political, connoting the franchise and right to organize, and social, connoting economic welfare and security. 2 5 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E Citizenship discourse encompasses both rights and obligations within the ‘public’ sphere. In its traditional, more limited, version, ‘public’ means ‘governmental,’ and ‘private’ includes the realms of market, waged work, and family. Public/private corresponds to state/civil society. Under this model, citizenship entails entitlements and duties to participate actively in the polit- ical affairs of the day (for example, by voting and the exercise of expressional rights). People of colour, women, children, and individuals without real property – groups who have historically suffered political disenfranchisement – have been to a significant extent excluded from this tra- ditional conception of citizenship. Progressives fought a long, uphill battle to bring the concept of citizenship into the paid work- place in the form of collective bargaining rights, minimum labour standards, and equal employ- ment opportunities. Even so, the expansion of citizenship rights into paid work, as progressives tra- ditionally fought for it, has incorporated a racialized, gendered breadwinner model. In other words, traditional progressivism effectively promotes a second version of the public/ private distinction, in which ‘public’ means government and economic activity, whereas ‘private’ denotes the family. Although the boundary between the public and private has shifted, citizenship obligations contin- ue to incorporate racial and gender hierarchies and bias by excluding those who are economically disenfranchised, that is, insufficiently attached to waged work. Little conceptual progress has been made to imagine viable alternative forms of citizenship participation in other arenas. Specifically, citizenship obligations until heretofore have not included care-giving, and correspondingly, the image of the citizen does not include care-givers, whether wives, servants, or slaves. As previously disenfranchised groups have acquired formal, political status as citizens, with rights to vote, contract, own property, and associate, the dominant political culture has embraced the assumption that ‘equality’ has been achieved – that all individuals, regardless of race, class, and gender, stand on an equal playing field and can negotiate in markets and fami- ly structures as equals in the pursuit of economic welfare and security. Thus, the traditional dis- course of citizenship reinforces formal conceptions of equality, individualism, and self-reliance, and the view that individual responsibility (merit and effort) is the primary method for cor- recting economic and power imbalances. An imagery of citizenship focused on independent and autonomous individuals possessing rights and obligations within the public sphere legitimizes the correlative imagery of ‘dependants’ – people who are not full citizens because they are not in waged work. Paid work becomes the forum within which social citizenship can be recog- nized. In other words, the ‘private’ pre-legal rules of the market become the ‘public’ cultural sphere through which citizenship obligations can be fulfilled. It is very difficult to erect a broad, multi-layered programme for economic redistribution on such a platform. Indeed, from this, it is a short step to rhetoric emphasizing the need for wel- fare recipients to be active and productive participants of society within the public sphere of waged work. This concept of citizenship – the white male breadwinner version – excludes wel- fare recipients cycling in and out of low-waged employment, juggling the demands of paid work and family responsibility, as well as care-givers who are not in the paid labour market. Like the statutory definitions of ‘worker’ that exclude low-waged workers and home-makers, building ‘social citizenship’ on the foundation of an unproblematized, liberal conception of who is a cit- izen risks excluding welfare recipients and others considered outside mainstream society.17 17 Note the current rhetorical deployment by the UK government of notions of ‘exclusion’ and ‘inclusion,’ often designating lone mothers as ‘excluded’ from society, reminiscent of the poverty discourse in Elizabethan times that viewed the pauper as outside the community, ie, in the poor house. On current UK welfare policy, see further Conaghan ‘Woman, Work and Family: A British Revolution’ in J Conaghan, RM Because the dominant discourse embraces formal, ahistorical conceptions of the individual, the citizen, and equality, concepts of social citizenship uncritically derived therefrom will not be sufficiently sensitive to the structural limitations of civic rights and entitlements in societies per- meated by illegitimate racial, gender, and class domination. Yet often left labour and welfare theorists have not attended to the highly gendered and racialized nature of citizenship as we know it, nor have they done much to re-envision the con- cept to include the life experiences and needs of the millions of people who cannot meet the conventionally defined obligations of citizenship.18 The forum for fulfilment of citizenship, even among progressive labour and welfare advocates, remains the public realm. Labour’s con- ception of social citizenship refers largely to collective action and minimum guarantees in the labour market. Jurists interpreting welfare laws valorize waged work as the privileged site of human self-realization.19 Not surprisingly, since the PRWORA, many progressive welfare lawyers have focused on assisting poor families to overcome barriers to participation in paid work. They have done so, however, without seriously challenging the mainstream tenet that government ‘interventions’- like welfare programmes – are presumptively inefficient and should be carefully limited to the role of ameliorating the contradictions, and correcting the imperfec- tions, of the market. A left political agenda that merely grafts some socio-economic rights onto the model of citizenship, albeit within discourses of workplace democracy and egalitarian fam- ily relations, fails to problematize its foundational concepts. Even if we were to develop a richer conception of participation, for example, by including care-giving activities currently denigrated because of the privileged place of politics and wage labour, it remains the case that citizenship discourse rest historically on notions of membership and participation in a particular polity or nation-state.20 Although this may not be logically entailed, membership is taken to imply exclusion, whether by social or geographic boundaries. But the nation-state as we know it owes more to conquest, racial exclusion, imperialism, and genocide than to the liberal-democratic revolutions and the progressive appeal of self-determi- nation.21 When labour and welfare academics and activists take the national context for grant- ed, we fail to grapple with the intricate connections linking social protection, labour, mobility of capital, and immigration, often, in ostrich-like fashion, hiding our heads in the sand in a time of increasing global economic integration. Re-Envisioning the Discourse of Redistribution 251 Fischl & K Klare (eds) Labour Law in an Era of Globalization: Transformative Practices and Possibilities (2002) 53-74. 18 Notable exceptions include JS O’Connor ‘Gender, Class and Citizenship in the Comparative Analysis of Welfare State Regimes: Theoretical and Methodological Issues’ (1993) 44 British J of Sociology 501; Yuval- Davis ‘Women, Citizenship and Difference’ (1997) 57 Feminist Rev 4; Orloff (note 8 above); R Lister ‘Citizenship: Towards a Feminist Synthesis’ (1997) 57 Feminist Rev 28. 19 See, eg, New York State Department of Social Services v Dublino, 413 US 405 (1973), and Brief of the Appellants, New York State Departments of Social Services and Labor and their Commissioners at 36: ‘…But work is not an obligation that makes less of a man[sic], but rather it makes more of a man. Tub work is more than doing a job, putting in time and collecting pay. Work is a source of interest, of friendship, and of activity that gives meaning and fulfillment to life…’ 20 For additional discussion of the idea of citizenship within the discursive framework of the nation-state, see further, Bosniak ‘Critical Reflection on “Citizenship” as a Progressive Aspiration’ in J Conaghan, RM Fischl & K Klare (eds) Labour Law in an Era of Globalization: Transformative Practices and Possibilities (2002) 339-352. 21 Recent US critical approaches to international law have begun to articulate more complex, multi-layered notions of borders. See, eg R Buchanan ‘Border Crossings: NAFTA, Regulatory Restructuring, and the Politics of Place’ (1995) 2 Indiana J of Global Legal Studies 371. 2 5 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E Of course, in light of the crisis of declining union power and the intensity of assaults on the wel- fare state, US labour and welfare advocates and theorists have understandably focused atten- tion on their domestic scene. However, in so doing, our rhetoric often reflects a nostalgia for isolationism. Labour’s nation-state focus is most evident in its fixation on collective bargaining as the privileged site of redistributional possibility. While this model has yielded many impor- tant victories, it rests on several increasingly problematical assumptions, including, for exam- ple, the assumption that nation-states can control the impact of capital flight and currency fluc- tuations; that immigration can be regulated through border enforcement of legal prohibitions established by nation-states; and that union density, even within a nation-state, will reach work- er-majority levels and incorporate waged workers not currently included within any collective bargaining framework, so that vertical redistribution (from management to labour) through collective bargaining poses only limited risks of exacerbating horizontal inequalities (between higher paid unionized and non-unionized, low-wage workers). While perhaps some of these assumptions were plausible in the postwar years, for reasons discussed below, social reality is rapidly pushing in a different direction. Labour and welfare law cannot be viewed as ‘domestic issues’ within any nation-state. In light of currently unfold- ing trends toward global economic integration, a concept of citizenship anchored solely in the nation-state is anachronistic. The expansion and liberalization of trade, increased volume and mobility of capital and financing, breakdown of the Bretton Woods mechanisms for currency control, portability of many production techniques and equipment, and the emergence of third world manufacturing all sharply call into question the assumption that employment and social policy can be made within a nation-state framework. All of this is in addition to the moral and political imperative for people in the developed world to accept responsibility for addressing the gross maldistribution of wealth and resources on a world scale. Mainstream US politicians and, regrettably, many progressive critics, discuss ‘transitioning’ welfare recipients to work under the PRWORA within a framework based not only on a dichotomized image of welfare recipient versus waged worker, but also on a domestic labour market, as if the US had no links to the rest of the world. But economic life in the US involves massive cross-border capital and labour flows and integrated, cross-border production chains. Changes in labour or welfare laws in other countries often have important ramifications in the US (and vice-versa), whether in the form of human migration, capital migration, or rising nat- uralizations of legal immigrants. More restrictive immigration policy, rather than reducing migration, may produce more undocumented immigrants, creating a quite different impact on US low-wage labour markets than that produced by legal immigration. Progressive lawyers attempting to develop new institutional mechanisms for redistribution must grapple carefully with the tension between capital mobility and restrictions on the free movement of persons. The relationship between the US and Mexico highlights the implications of cross-border labour, welfare, immigration, and trade interactions, particularly the impact of anti-NAFTA and anti-immigrant rhetoric on US welfare policy and naturalizations, and the artificiality of borders vis-à-vis citizenship. US labour union opposition to the NAFTA in 1994 was often voiced as a fear of ‘losing US jobs to Mexico.’ Two years later, the PRWORA terminated the eligibility of legal immigrants, whether or not in waged work, for virtually all welfare pro- grammes. Mexicans formed the largest group of US legal immigrants by far, who had chosen not to naturalize as US citizens. Labour and welfare academics and activists condemned PRWORA, but there was virtually no self-critique as to whether labour’s anti-NAFTA position might have, however unintentionally, fed into racist, anti-Mexican, and anti-immigration atti- tudes that culminated in the disqualification of thousands of legal immigrants. In ratifying the NAFTA, one bone that Congress threw to labour was the NAFTA-Trade Adjustment Act providing additional weeks of UI benefits for retraining workers (excluding workers not covered by UI laws) who lose their jobs due to increased imports or capital flight generated by the NAFTA. As a result, US taxpayers are funding the extended UI and retraining of workers dislocated by US trade policy, at the same time as they are defunding many welfare benefits to low-waged welfare recipients and legal, often Mexican, immigrants. PRWORA’s targeting of immigrants and similar political developments (such as California’s Proposition 187 barring undocumented immigrants from receiving almost all education, social services, and health benefits) prompted the emergence of a new consciousness among legal Mexican immigrants in the US to become naturalized US citizens so that they could vote and participate fully politically. Until 1994, the number of naturalizations by Mexicans legally residing in the United States was fairly stable at about 20,000 per year. This development in turn has brought about profound changes in the political landscape. In 1994, the year that Californians adopted Proposition 187, naturalizations surged to 46,186, and in 1995, to 79,614. Most dramatically, in 1996 (the year the PRWORA was being debated and enacted), Mexico was the leading country-of-birth of persons naturalizing, with 254,988 or 24.4 per cent of total naturalizations.22 As naturalized citizens, these individuals enjoy greatly expanded legal rights to bring family members into the US. Thus the ironic result of anti-immigrant politics in the 1990s may be that even greater numbers of Mexican immigrants will settle in the US, nat- uralize and vote. This, in turn, raises questions about the effect of this additional supply of waged workers on both union density and decisions of companies to relocate cross-border. Juxtapose these developments to recent dramatic changes in Mexican laws relating to dual citizenship and the ability of non-residents to vote in Mexican elections. Recent legal changes allow Mexican non-residents to maintain dual citizenship. In particular, Mexican immigrants who are naturalized US citizens are now permitted to reclaim their Mexican citizenship.23 Mexico’s Congress enacted legislation, not yet implemented at the time of the 2000 election (in which the Institutional Revolutionary Party (PRI) was defeated for the first time since 1920 by the National Action Party (PAN)), which would allow non-resident Mexican citizens to vote in Mexican elections without returning to Mexico.24 Almost 10 million Mexicans more or less permanently residing in the US could be eligible to vote in Mexican elections and are expected to support either the PAN or the Party of the Democratic Revolution (PRD), Mexican political parties advocating the democratization of labour unions in Mexico.25 Thus the huge increase in US naturalizations by Mexicans (in turn opening the door for further immigration by fami- ly members) and the emergence of dual citizenship and dual voting privileges in Mexico could have broad implications for social protection and low-wage labour in both the US and Mexico, Re-Envisioning the Discourse of Redistribution 253 22 US Dept of Justice, Immigration and Naturalization Service, 1996 Statistical Yearbook of the Immigration and Naturalization Service (1997) 152. Of course, there were other legal changes which factored into this increase, most specifically the numbers of undocumented immigrants allowed to naturalize pursuant to the Immigration Reform and Control Act of 1986, Pub L No 99-603, 100 Stat 3359 (1986). 23 Constitucion Politica de los Estados Unidos Mexicanos, art 30 (amended 1996). 24 Although the Chamber of Deputies had approved a package implementing this election reform, the Senate (controlled by the PRI) allowed the measure to die in July 1999. JF Smith ‘Vote Denied to Mexicans Living Abroad’ (1999) 2 July Los Angeles Times at A1. 25 PJ McDonnell ‘US Votes Could Sway Mexico’s Next Election’ (1999) 15 February Los Angeles Times at A1. On labour politics in a Mexican context, see further C de Buen Unna ‘Mexican Trade Unionism in a Time of Transition’ in J Conaghan, RM Fischl & K Klare (eds) Labour Law in an Era of Globalization: Transformative Practices and Possibilities (2002) 401-416. 2 5 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E exemplifying why citizenship attached to the nation-state is an increasingly antiquated concept. Most lawyers working to revivify the concept of social citizenship and enlist it in the service of progressive causes reflexively and unconsciously adopt the nation-state perspective or, at best, leave that aspect of citizenship discourse unexamined. But ‘social citizenship’ will never become the emblem of redistributive politics and transformative aspirations until it is re-imag- ined from a thoroughly globalized perspective. V Conclusion The three legal discourses discussed in this essay individually and cumulatively privilege labour markets and waged work, marginalize broad redistributive agendas as exceptions, and obscure the understanding that all legal questions have distributive implications. Family and market are constructed as private, pre-legal, and autonomous from the state. The role of back- ground legal rules in entrenching power imbalances within those societal spheres is ignored. Labour lawyers and welfare lawyers have both contributed to the discursive construction of income distribution as somehow independent of state action: labour lawyers by valorizing labour markets and collective bargaining as the privileged site of income distribution, while at the same time viewing welfare law as a ‘special case’ of state intervention, and welfare lawyers by fixating on government transfer policy and largely ignoring private law. Thus welfare law becomes a market corrective technique, an adjunct to private law, rather than a redistributive hub. Likewise social insurance and social assistance statutes, often fought for and defended by the left, separate ‘workers’ and ‘non-workers’ through artificial definitions that support the creation of partial identities. When labour lawyers argue for enhanced UI benefits on the ground that society should protect and reward primary-sector wage-earners, they are ‘other- ing’ many potential allies within waged work and denigrating non-waged work, thereby per- petuating a hierarchy of market work over family care-giving performed primarily by women. The discourse of citizenship perpetuates a male model of participation in the ‘public’ spheres of liberal democratic institutions and waged work as the means of fulfilling citizenship obli- gations and therefore acquiring full social status. And traditional citizenship discourse legiti- mates first-world protectionist policies and attitudes that perpetuate gross global inequalities, while ignoring the implications of increasing global interdependence. The discourses of these quite disparate fields reinforce one another. However unwittingly, progressive legal advocacy often reaffirms the prevailing political ‘consensus’ – that policies privileging the nation-state, market, and traditional family are natural and those dismantling the welfare state are inevitable. In other words, the rhetoric of many progressive labour and welfare theoreticians and activists assumes that the identities constructed by statutory social welfare programmes accu- rately reflect a pre-legal order providing the appropriate framework for self-fulfilment and cit- izenship activity. The reaffirmation of the free market and the traditional family as the ‘correct’ framework for dealing with domestic and global income disparities – without challenging and transforming the background rules that structure markets and families – perpetuates class, racial and gender inequality and disempowerment. I do not suggest that we must devise a single, integrated, cross-border low-wage labour and poverty policy. But we must challenge ourselves to look beyond our limited or narrowly defined constituencies, to frame new questions about labour and welfare strategy within an increasing- ly globalized economy. My hope is that, by increasing the amount and sophistication of dia- logue among social welfare, low-wage labour, immigration, family and economic globalization discourses, scholars and activists in these linked fields can begin to disrupt and undermine the ways legal culture legitimates and reinforces the social and economic status quo. This essay challenges both labour and welfare lawyers to enter more rigorously into interdisciplinary self- critique as a basis for intellectual renewal and the creation of a transformative vision of the pol- itics of redistribution. Re-Envisioning the Discourse of Redistribution 255 Opening the Door to More Equality R O S S Z U C K E R Professor of Political Science, Lander College for Men, Kew Gardens Hills The (Greek) colonists tended to divide the land they settled into equal shares, reflect- ing the egalitarian tendency inherent in the ethical system of the yeoman farmers in the mother cities.1 I Income Inequality and Contemporary Political Theory The idea of egalitarian rules of income distribution runs against the grain of much, if not most, of contemporary political theory.2 This is curious considering the fact that contemporary polit- ical theory is full of theories claiming to be egalitarian. Ronald Dworkin announces that ‘egal- itarian liberalism is the dominant substantive theory of justice — indeed it is hardly even much challenged.’3 It may in fact be the dominant theory of justice, but it is, nevertheless, not well disposed toward rules that distribute market-generated inequalities of income more equally and is not egalitarian, at least in that way. (It only supports rules that redistribute inequalities stem- ming from social and natural background that are not generated by the market.) Similarly, com- munitarian opponents of liberal egalitarianism have not been formulating such rules,4 not to mention the position of liberalism’s conservative challengers.5 The Anglo-American moral and political theories developed since World War II are more concerned about inequalities of so-called basic liberty, opportunity, social background, natural talents, and capabilities than they are about inequality of income. Many, perhaps most, of them accept the legitimacy of market outcomes, including income inequalities, as long as they arise under (variously stipulated) conditions of equal opportunity. As Rawls writes, ‘[O]nce a suit- able minimum is provided by transfers, it may be perfectly fair that the rest of total income be settled by the price system.’6 The newest school of political theory, real libertarianism, seeks to justify a basic income guarantee, but this measure is not coupled with a rule that limits relative inequality above the basic income. Few on the left concern themselves with the concentration of income and wealth in the US, though it is warranted by the fact that ‘the United States ha[s] just experienced the most colos- 1 D Kagan, S Ozment & FM Turner The Western Heritage to 1715 (2001) at 48-49. 2 I would like to express my appreciation to Elizabeth Wagner for her comments on a draft of this paper. 3 R Dworkin ‘Why We Are All Liberals’ paper presented at the Program for the Study of Law, Philosophy & Social Theory NYU School of Law 19 October 1995 at 1. 4 MJ Sandel Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (1982). Sandel’s discussion implies that unequal income is justifiable if it is necessary in order to further a communal purpose. 5 See R Nozick Anarchy, State, and Utopia (1974). 6 J Rawls A Theory of Justice (1971) at 277. sal [upward] redistribution of wealth in world history.’7 Some left liberals are concerned, not about very unequal income and wealth, but about egalitarian democratic theories that conceive of democracy in a way that entails strong economic equality. Believing that real progress toward economic equality is unlikely, these left liberals conclude that full democracy, requiring strong economic equality, is unrealistic. ‘[T]here are good reasons,’ writes Stephen Elkin, ‘to think this [real progress toward economic equality] cannot be the case. Economic theory suggests that strong economic equality is not available to us, not least because it will run afoul of the need for economic incentives required if there is to be a high level of economic prosperity.’8 But the pendulum of income and wealth distribution has swung widely in the past hundred years. In 1944, the 94 percent top marginal tax rate on the highest incomes significantly reduced inequal- ity in the US.9 Now the US has just experienced a huge upward distribution of income and wealth. With these swings here and those in Europe due to the adoption and rejection of the mixed economy, why is it unthinkable that a future change in public opinion could produce a large downward redistribution? The old economic orthodoxy on incentives continues to have remarkable traction within contemporary political theory. Economic theory’s mere suggestion about the need for incentives is enough to wash away the possibility of a more egalitarian society. Old ideas can be so author- itative that many contemporary political theorists do not even ask if society could achieve ade- quate productivity with substantially reduced income differentials. Senior executives received as much as 200 or even 2000 times the annual incomes of their low- est paid workers in the US in recent years.10 But a productive economy can evidently be achieved using much lower multiples. About 35 times the annual income of the lowest paid worker ade- quately drove the American and Japanese economies in decades of strong growth during the twen- tieth century.11 And it is possible that lower multiples might have sufficed. Moreover, much of a person’s salary does not have to do with incentives anyway. Salaries of senior executives in major corporations have as much to do with power as they do with incentives, as law professors Lucien Bebchuk, Jesse Fried and David Walker demonstrated in their analysis of executive compensa- tion.12 Senior executives and corporate compensation committees are in a position to reward sen- ior executives handsomely and they take advantage of the situation. Liberals and left liberals who say ‘economic theory’ considers high income inequality necessary for incentives give a one-sided account of its position. Mainline economic theorists are not all of one mind on this. John Maynard Keynes differed from the economic orthodoxy of his day, which is not much different from current economic orthodoxy in this regard, when he said ‘There are valuable human activities which require the motive of money-making and the environment of pri- vate wealth ownership for their full fruition. … But it is not necessary for the stimulation of these activities … that the game should be played for such high stakes. … Much lower stakes will serve the purpose equally well, as soon as the players are accustomed to them.’13 Opening the Door to More Equality 257 7 Sam Pizzigati ‘The Left and the Rich’ Paper presented at the Global Left Forum, New York City (2005) at 1. 8 SL Elkin ‘Notes on the Old Political Science for the Present Age’ (2004) 1 The Good Society at 4. 9 S Pizzigati ‘The Left and the Rich’ (note 7 above) at 5. 10 P Bennis ‘Talking Points: Iraq, The UN, & US Corporations’ (2003) Web publication by United for Peace and Justice: http://unitedforpeace.org/article.php?id=2031 3 at 1. The 2000 figure refers to the multiple of Lockheed CEO Martin Vance Coffman’s 2004 pay package over that of the entry level soldier. 11 ‘CEO Pay in ’98: Insanity Marches On’ (1999) 5 Too Much 1 at 3. 12 See L Bebchuk, J Fried & D Walker ‘Managerial Power and Rent Extraction in the Design of Executive Compensation’ (2002) 69 University of Chicago LR 751. 13 The General Theory of Employment, Interest, and Money (1964) at 374. 2 5 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E The government of the United States grapples more with the problem of unequal opportunity than with unequal income and wealth (not to say the amount of its attention to the former inequalities is adequate). One might expect that policies to reduce unequal opportunity and capability would indirectly reduce inequalities of income and wealth. But inequalities of income and wealth proved intractable in late twentieth and early twenty-first century America and some other countries. Indeed they grew considerably during the last three decades. A compre- hensive analysis of contemporary inequalities of income and wealth, recently conducted by Sam Pizzigati, shows that they play a very large part in the story of contemporary America.14 Contemporary political theorists, for the most part, have not responded to evidence of the intractability of inequalities of income and wealth by developing justifications for rules of more equal distribution of income. That they have not done so serves to support a highly unequal system. Prevailing high levels of income inequality make it crucial to reconsider the direction that contemporary political theorists have chosen. Can contemporary political theory be refor- mulated to provide a justification for more direct and effective remedies to income inequality? The question turns, I think, on whether philosophical foundations for rules of egalitarian dis- tribution of income and wealth can be formulated. The income-inegalitarianism of contemporary theorists derives to a significant extent from its patrimony in the work of the distinguished philosopher John Rawls.15 They work within his paradigm in A Theory of Justice (1971) or within his related paradigm in Political Liberalism (1993). Rawls’s highly influential 1971 book supports almost all of the forms of equality then known except equality of income and wealth. Theory treats income and wealth very different- ly from the basic liberties, lexically ordering the latter before the former. While basic liberties are subject to strictly equal distribution, income and wealth are relegated to treatment under the ‘difference’ principle. As a result, equality of liberty and of opportunity is required and unlimited inequalities of incomes and wealth are authorized as long as they work to the advan- tage of the worst off. Inequalities of income and wealth are deemed just, because and insofar as they generate incentives that augment the GNP and yield a larger portion for the worst off than they otherwise get. Since A Theory of Justice was published thirty four years ago, theorists have diverged from Rawls on many points, but they tend to share his position on income inequalities, which may be characterized as follows: 1. Income inequality is not a primary concern. 2. Income inequality is justifiable. 3. The condition of the worst off is the major concern of distributive justice. 4. Market outcomes, and market inequalities, are legitimate for the rest of the population, so long they arise under equal opportunity. 5. The height of the income hierarchy cannot be limited by rules of egalitarian redistribution. Many contemporary theories of economic justice stand or fall on the veracity of these proposi- tions. Rawls attempts to justify a principle authorizing extreme inequalities of income and wealth 14 S Pizzigati Greed and Good (2005). 15 M Nussbaum calls him ‘the most distinguished moral and political philosopher of our age’: ‘The Enduring Significance of John Rawls’ (2001) The Chronicle of Higher Education B7 at B7. by appealing to the judgment of all. Everyone in the ‘original position’ (a hypothetical condi- tion designed to yield a just choice) would consent to that position, he claims. But the reason- ing of the participants seems flawed to me. They err, firstly, in supposing that inequalities of income and wealth are mere matters of the ‘good’ rather than of the ‘right’. As anyone can test out by trying to act upon one’s choice of consumption bundle without any income or wealth, income and wealth are means of freedom. For this reason, inequalities of income and wealth are inequalities of freedom and they are, therefore, subject to control by the principle of right. Mistaking inequalities of income and wealth as matters of the good, the participants downgrade the importance of inequalities of income and wealth relative to the so-called basic liberties. This decision then leads them to authorize unlimited inequality of income and wealth for incentive purposes, as long as these steps benefit the worst off.16 The last two steps are not warranted, however, because income and wealth are means of freedom. The choices afforded by income and wealth are as basic as those Rawls deems ‘basic liberties.’ Far greater caution then needs to be exercised before allowing unlimited unequal distribution of them. The reasoning of the participants seems flawed, secondly, because their concerns are parochial in comparison with the broad scope of justice. What they consent to, the difference principle, is very limited in its concerns. The difference principle holds that inequalities of income and wealth are just if they are to the advantage of the worst off members of society. The participants give their consent to this principle out of a grave concern that they may wind up among the worst off members of society.17 But they do not reflect much about inequalities over the rest of the income spectrum, though the worst off may be only a fraction of the total in a society with a mushrooming middle class. The upshot is a philosophical justification for a wel- fare state. The participants in the original position are blithely unconcerned that it might be accompanied by widening inequalities between the middle class and the upper class and between different strata within the middle class. Yet this is exactly what has come to pass in the United States.18 Indeed it is a dominant feature of contemporary life in America and increas- ingly in other countries as well. The condition of the worst off members of society is, undoubtedly, an urgent matter from the standpoint of justice. But the difference principle is not a principle of justice, in my view, because the concerns of justice are general; they do not privilege one group, even the least advantaged, to such an extent that they withhold full consideration from everyone else. Incomes of people at the top of the income hierarchy supply them with tremendously more freedom than the incomes at the bottom supply the worst off with (if they receive any income). However, there are significant dif- ferences between the incomes of other individuals all along the income gradient. The inequality of freedom between someone who has 20 billion dollars worth of means of freedom and someone who has little or no financial means of freedom is more terrible than the inequality of freedom between someone with a 625,000 dollar per year income and another with a 40,000 dollar income, but justice cannot ignore the latter inequality. Because many of the income differences along the entire income hierarchy involve substantial differences between the means of freedom available to individuals, justice is concerned with achieving real progress toward equal means of freedom all along the income hierarchy, not just with the especially objectionable inequalities in the means of freedom between the worst off and the best off. This is not to say, however, that the general rule of economic justice would level income. Some inequalities of income may be necessary for equal Opening the Door to More Equality 259 16 As to their being unlimited in Rawls’s theory, see Rawls (note 6 above) at 151. 17 Rawls (note 6 above) at 153. 18 See R Zucker ‘On the Future of the Justice Debates’ (2004) 13 The Good Society 67 at 76-77. 2 6 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E freedom, due to differences between individuals’ consumption and production ambitions. But many of them do not result from differences between individuals’ consumption and production ambitions.19 To this extent they are inimical to equal freedom. Rawls’s focus on unequal opportunity for education and training suggests an implicit empha- sis on supply side determinants of income inequality. Market rewards to productive agents depend, however, not only on training and education, but also on the demand for what is being produced. Since extreme inequalities of income naturally arise from within the market, even under conditions of fair equality of opportunity, equal opportunity rules exercise less control over income inequality than some might suppose. As William Julius Wilson demonstrated in The Truly Disadvantaged (1987), income inequality rose among blacks during the 1980s despite greater equality of opportunity afforded by the civil rights laws and legislation passed during 1960s and ’70s. These facts suggest that egalitarian liberalism has shortchanged equality by emphasizing equality of opportunity at the expense of real progress toward equality of incomes. Any theorist concerned with limiting the range of income inequality might recognize a need to try to formulate principles of relative distribution of income, not just rules regarding capabilities or opportunities. As economic inequality grew in the 1970s and 1980s, liberal theorists brought out a seeming- ly new approach, known as ‘liberal egalitarianism.’ In ‘Equality of Resources — Part Two’ Ronald Dworkin argued that inequalities of income and wealth that result from social background, nat- ural talents, and brute luck are not outcomes of free choice. These inequalities are therefore incon- sistent with equal freedom or real equality of resources and they should be nullified by optional insurance plans.20 Apart from concern with these sorts of inequalities, liberal egalitarians accept the legitimacy of market outcomes, including extreme inequalities of wealth and income. Inequalities of income and wealth could have been significantly reduced if countries imple- mented liberal egalitarian principles for dealing with the ramifications of social background, natural talents, and unequal opportunity. But extreme inequalities of income and wealth would not be eliminated by such measures. Capital-based market systems have internal processes that would generate extreme inequalities despite measures to offset the income-effects of social background and natural talent. For example, liberal egalitarianism does not reduce demand- side causes of inequalities of income. People with equal talents and social backgrounds can make extremely different incomes depending on consumer preferences for their products. During the 1980s and 1990s contemporary political and moral theory supplemented its focus on the worst off, equal opportunity, social background, and natural talents by adding an emphasis on capabilities. This change roughly tracked the shift in the American economy from a capital-goods producing economy to a service economy and a high technology economy. The new economy is one where possession/ non-possession of marketable capabilities rivals ownership/non-ownership of cap- ital as a determinant of income.21 Amartya Sen provided a philosophical justification for increased governmental and societal emphasis on the development of capabilities.22 In doing so, he broadened the moral scope of liberal theory considerably. But his formulation emphasizes capabilities over incomes and the principles that he proposes do not directly regulate the inequality of income. Sen 19 For more on this, see R Zucker ‘Democracy and Economic Justice,’ Paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Political Science Association 23 August 2003. 20 R Dworkin ‘What Is Equality: Part 2: Equality of Resources’ (1981)10 Philosophy and Public Affairs 283. 21 C Graham and S Pettinato Happiness and Hardship: Opportunity and Insecurity in New Market Economies (2002) at 41. 22 A Sen Choice, Welfare and Measurement (1982) at 367; A Sen Inequality Reexamined (1992) at 19-22. For an interesting, recent treatment of capabilities, see DP Levine ‘Poverty, Capabilities, and Freedom’ (2003) 15 Review of Political Economy 101. contended that every basal equality entails a secondary inequality.23 In a system of thought which accords priority to capabilities, this means that capability equality can require income inequality or, in other words, that income inequality is justified for the sake of capability equality. The principles proposed by the foregoing liberal theories could have some beneficial effect upon economic inequality if they were implemented, but they would not adequately or direct- ly reduce income inequality. Each one of them authorizes a wide scope for market-generated inequalities of income and wealth. These inequalities cannot be dealt with satisfactorily by lib- eral egalitarianism’s roundabout methods. To rectify them direct limits need to be placed on the scope of market generated inequalities. Capping incomes is not necessary, however. A rule of redistribution that strictly equalizes part of a person’s income and leaves another part of it unregulated would substantially reduce inequality without a cap. The central question for this article is whether such a rule is morally defensible. Against the background of roundabout liberalism, ‘real libertarianism’ presents a welcome change. Finally there is a contemporary political theory that focuses directly on income and offers rules of income distribution. Van Parijs claims that this economic philosophy would pro- vide real liberty if adopted.24 I suspect that it would not promote liberty as much as he main- tains. The basic income guarantee provides basic means of freedom, but above this floor peo- ple can have extremely unequal means of freedom. No limit is defined for the height of the income hierarchy above the floor. Real libertarianism is a more direct form of liberalism in its treatment of income, but it is not a form of real liberty. Direct libertarianism, if you will, does not answer to the challenge of 21st century income in- equality. Its central concept, a basic income, represents a throw back to Rawls’s emphasis on the worst off or a way of realizing his emphasis on this group. The provision of a basic income adjusts the height of the floor, but — like previous welfare entitlements — allows extreme income inequality between the upper, middle, and lower strata. Van Parijs explicitly formulates the basic income theory as a lex- imining approach, which places tremendous weight on the condition of the worst off rather than on general inequality, just as the difference principle does.25 Sounding like Nozick, Van Parijs character- izes egalitarian rules of income distribution as violations of freedom and of basic security rights.26 Real libertarianism leaves in its wake the same question that the rest of contemporary polit- ical theory does: Is real progress toward equality of income justifiable? II A Social Theory of Reward for Economic Contributions (A) INTRODUCTION A theory of distributive justice sets forth principles stating that resources should be distributed in a certain way. Principles of just distribution are arrived at by reasoning guided in line with ideals of justice. One of these ideals is that people should be rewarded in proportion to their economic con- tributions. This ideal, the reasoning, and the principles comprise a branch of justice known as the ‘ethics of reward for economic contributions’ or as ‘ethics of dueness for economic contributions.’ Another branch of distributive justice, the ‘ethics of community,’ has a distinct ideal of justice: that Opening the Door to More Equality 261 23 A Sen Inequality (note 22 above) at 19-22. 24 P van Parijs Real Freedom for All (1995). 25 Van Parijs Real Freedom (note 24 above) at 25, 33. 26 Van Parijs Real Freedom (note 24 above) at 25. 2 6 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E the members of a community, united for the pursuit of some common end or ends, are entitled to share in the end(s) of association, to the extent that it is a community. Still another branch of jus- tice, the ‘ethics of freedom,’ holds that resources should be so distributed that they contribute, as much as possible, to the realization of freedom. I will sketch a derivation of principles of just dis- tribution within the first two branches of distributive justice. Ethicists of reward for contributions usually take the position that unequal rewards are jus- tified because some individuals make bigger contributions to the creation of value than others do. In fact, they usually think extremely unequal rewards are morally supportable as long as they are proportionate to contributions. Reward proportionate to contributions sounds like the standard distributive ethics in economics, but actually it is not. JR Hicks showed that the mar- ginal product of labour or capital does not determine the wage or rent; it only equals the wage or rent.27 Thereafter most neoclassical economists ceased to view the ethics of reward as a sci- entific ethics of distribution. The neoclassical theory nevertheless continues to provide a major underpinning for the ethics of unequal reward. However, ethicists rather than neoclassical theorists are for the most part the ones that treat this ethics as a scientifically well-founded approach. In neoclassical theory, the system is one where individuals receive unequal incomes partly because of differences between their labour-leisure choices and partly because the selling prices of the final products (which indirectly affect factor prices) are affected by consumer preferences that are different to the point of non-comparability. Since differences between individuals are vital to its account of the determination of major system variables, neoclassical theory has an elective affinity for the ethics of unequal reward. In view of this, it is not surprising that some normative economists (Hayek, Zamagni) and ethicists outside of the profession continue to uphold principles of unequal remuneration based on different contributions. Ostensibly value-free microeconomic theory perpetuates the ethics of reward for unequal contributions in the contemporary era. The modern economic ethic of unequal reward can be assessed by reexamining the theory of the determination of economic value on which it is based. The theory of economic value is a theory of the determination of the value of commodities, that is, goods and services bought and sold on the market. As neoclassical theorists contend, individual contributions differ. But in what ways and to what extent? I will argue that individual contributions are also similar in some ways that ethicists have not taken into account when calculating appropriate rewards for contributions. If forms of equal contributions can be demonstrated, then these equalities must be taken into account when calculating just remuneration. The implications of their incorpora- tion into an ethics of dueness are clear: people have been remunerated more unequally than they should have been and income should be distributed more equally than it is. The theory of value presupposed by most theorists of reward is itself premised on a certain assumption about the kind of economic agents that make economic contributions. Producers are assumed to be the only kind of economic agents that can make economic contributors, since they are the only ones that can create economic value. The labour theory of value or the pro- duction theory of value was put forth by classical liberal theorists (eg Locke), classical political economist (eg Smith) and by Marx. Theorists of reward from the classical liberalism to the pres- ent day have tended to base their ethics upon an essentially classical theory of value and of con- tributions. In their assumption of a classical theory of value, contemporary theorists of reward for contributions have not found themselves much challenged. When they are challenged it is usually on other grounds. Encountering little challenge to their underlying theory of value, con- 27 JR Hicks The Theory of Wages (1963) [1932]. temporary theorists of reward have not provided any defense of this approach. Their assump- tion that only producers create value clearly is at odds with the established position of modern, or ‘neoclassical’ economic theory, which holds that consumers, not only producers, help to determine the value of commodities. Rewards theorists do not consider the implications of this for the ethics of reward because they do not take it much into account. Neoclassical theorists also do not bring out the full ethical implications of their value theory. In particular, they have not explored the possibility that consumers’ part in the creation of value can be considered to be a contribution which can accrue entitlements for the value they create. (B) DO CONSUMERS QUALIFY AS CONTRIBUTORS? The foregoing analysis raises a serious problem for the ethics of reward for contributions. Do consumers meet the criteria for remuneration under a theory of reward for economic contribu- tions? The theory of reward is one that divides up rewards in proportion to contributions. As such, it must register any human source of economic creation. On this theory, inanimate objects and animals do not accrue entitlements for contributions, any more than they are entitled to any other sorts of rights. They can be protected, though, by fiduciary arrangements made on their behalf. An activity can qualify as an economically creative action if it contributes to the creation of the value of commodities. Consumer activities qualify as economically creative activities because they contribute to the determination of value and, therefore, satisfy the fore- going criterion of economically creative action. For this reason, consumer activities inexorably accrue moral titles for their contributions, on a principle of dueness. Consumer activities, such as the pursuit of want satisfaction or need satisfaction, display the same qualities that entitle producers to reward for their contributions. Producer contributions qualify because and insofar as they help to create value in the sense of exchange value, not merely use-value for the person himself or herself. But consumer contributions can meet this test as well. Neoclassical models of the economy in a condition of general economic equilibri- um show that consumer preferences help to determine relative prices or exchange values. Producer contributions qualify for remuneration because and insofar as they make socially val- ued contributions. Consumer contributions meet this test too. The effect of consumer prefer- ences upon relative prices shows that they are socially valued. Since consumers meet all of the requirements for remuneration for contributions that producers meet, they qualify for remu- neration proportionate to their contributions, just as producers do. To accord remuneration only to producers and to deny it to consumers would be, in a word, unjust. One might object that producer and consumer contributions differ in other ways which preclude the latter from entitlement to rewards. Productive activities, one might argue, involve effort and they are disutilities, whereas preference satisfaction is pleasurable, effortless, and has utility. But productive activities do not compare to consumptive activities as labour or effort does to satisfac- tion. Robert Lane points out that ‘[i]t is in work, not in consumption and, as research reports show, not even in leisure, where most people engage in activities that they find most satisfying, where they learn to cope with their human and natural environments, and where they learn about themselves. The economists’ ideas that work is the sacrifice or disutility that earns for workers the benefits or utilities of consumption is … quite false.’28 If productive activities can be due rewards for contri- butions notwithstanding the fact that they can be satisfying, then consumer activities and wants cannot be disqualified for rewards simply because they are satisfying. And, if consumer activities Opening the Door to More Equality 263 28 R Lane The Market Experience (1991) at 235. 2 6 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E are disqualified for rewards because they are satisfying, then work must be disqualified for remu- neration as well — since it is satisfying for most people too. In some of the leading contemporary theories of reward for contributions, contribution to the value of commodities, rather than the subjective experience of toil and trouble, is the major basis of reward for contributions. It would be inconsistent with this standpoint to preclude consumer activities, like the pursuit of want satisfaction, from receiving rewards for their contributions to value. Friedrich von Hayek argued that producers should be remunerated in proportion, not to the subjective experience of toil and trouble expended in production, but to the value of the product as determined by the market.29 Someone who enjoys tinkering, effortlessly invents a new widget, and sells it for a million dollars, is entitled to the market value of the widget in Hayekian ethics. Likewise a virtuoso pianist who practices constantly, but whom no one is willing to pay to hear, does not deserve any remuneration. Contemporary ethicists have not however drawn the implica- tions of this argument for rewarding consumers for their value contributions. If producer activities should be rewarded for contributions to value, not for the ‘toil and trouble’ they involve, then con- sumer activities can be due rewards for their contributions to value. (C) DO CONSUMERS REALLY MAKE CONTRIBUTIONS? Thomas Spragens, a professor of political theory at Duke University, argues that the social the- ory of rewards that I have presented is unpersuasive.30 The egalitarian rewards for consumer contributions are not warranted because consumer preferences, wants, and needs do not help to create economic value. He also objects to my claim that consumers play a role in the deter- mination of value in neoclassical economics. This last objection surprises me because the sup- ply and demand graphs in almost every microeconomics textbook show consumers helping to determine relative prices and, in this sense, to create value. Moreover, mathematical models of general economic equilibrium are even clearer that postulated consumer preferences and the state of technological knowledge help to determine prices.31 Spragens’ objection needs to be considered, however, because the egalitarian theory of reward cannot be valid if the underlying theory of value, involving a role for consumers, is wrong. ‘Needs become contributions to the creation of economic value,’ he writes, ‘only when they are backed by the resources to make them ‘effective,’ and that results only when those with the needs have produced something others want in order to generate the wherewithal to make their demand effective’.32 Since consumer wants, preferences, and needs do not make a contribution to the value of commodities, he thinks that the consumer theory of reward cannot be right. Spragens is correct to the extent that consumer preferences cannot help to determine relative prices if the consumer has no purchasing power. But from this point he moves to dismiss the possibility that consumer needs or preferences contribute to the value of commodities. My account of neoclassical economic theory does not deny the fact that consumer preferences can- not help to determine relative prices unless consumers have purchasing power. Moreover, the theory of value that I employ, which is not quite the same as neoclassical theory’s approach, does not deny it and is not refuted by it. The fact that consumer preferences have to be combined with purchasing power to have an effect 29 FA von Hayek The Constitution of Liberty (1960) at 94-97. 30 T Spragens ‘Review Essay: Justice, Consensus, and Boundaries: Assessing Political Liberalism’ (2003) 31 Political Theory 589 at 592. 31 G Debreu Theory of Value: An Axiomatic Analysis of Economic Equilibrium (1959). 32 Spragens ‘Review Essay’ (note 30 above) at 592. on prices does not mean that they cannot help to create value. It just means that they cannot help to create value without purchasing power. When Spragens denies that consumer preferences help to create value (because they can only do so when combined with purchasing power), he assumes that the influence of preferences is absolutely indistinguishable from the contribution which pur- chasing power makes. But they are distinguishable, though not wholly separable. Labour cannot engage in commodity production unless it is combined with capital in a production process, but that does not prevent labour from contributing to the creation of value. Everything in an interde- pendent neoclassical system effects prices through its relation to other variables, but that does not prevent them from making distinguishable contributions of their own. As I have already noted, when Spragens reduces the influence of consumers upon prices to the value of the resources that they (in their capacity as producers) obtain from producing things, he then denies that consumer wants form part of the value-creation process. He is attempting to reduce the role of the consumer in price determination to production, so that production appears to be the underlying source of value. But neoclassical economic theory is not really reductive in the specific way Spragens suggests that it is. Such theory accords consumer preferences relative autonomy in the process of creating value. Their role can be seen by considering a neoclassical model of gener- al economic equilibrium. If we alter the consumer preferences in the model, without changing the endowments (in this case of labour or wheat), relative prices change, suggesting, contrary to Spragens, that they make a distinguishable contribution to value. To illustrate, let us consider a standard neoclassical 2 x 2 x 2 general equilibrium model of the economy with decreasing returns to scale production functions. Specifications of the Model w1..price of input 1 w2..price of input 2 p1..price of good 1 p2..price of good 2 s1 1.. share of profits in industry 1 owned by person 1 100% of π1 s1 2.. share of profits in industry 1 owned by person 2 0% of π1 s2 1.. share of the profits of industry 2 owned by person 1 0% of π2 s2 2.. share of profits of industry 2 owned by person 2 100% of π2 q1..quantity of produced commodity 1 q2..quantity of produced commodity 2 v1..labour, v2.. land v1 1.. consumer 1’s endowment of input 1 (labour) v2 1.. consumer 1’s endowment of input 2 (land) v1 2.. consumer 2’s endowment of input 1 v2 2.. consumer 2’s endowment of input 2 v1..the total endowment of labour Let us suppose that the total endowment of labour is 20. v2..the total endowment of land. Let us suppose that the total endowment of land is 16. x1..wheat x2..wool x1 1.. amount of produced good 1 consumed by person 1 x2 1.. amount of produced good 2 consumed by person 1 x1 2.. amount of produced good 1 consumed by person 2 x2 2.. amount of produced good 2 consumed by person 2 Opening the Door to More Equality 265 2 6 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E Utility functions: Consumer 1 U1 = (x1 1) (x2 1) Consumer 2 U2 = (x1 1) (x2 1) Production functions: Wheat production (Good 1; Labour intensive) q1 = (v1 1) (v2 1) Wool production (Good 2; Land intensive) q2 = (v1 2) (v2 2) Let us choose as the numeraire good. Solving the system of equations for this model, I obtained the following results:33 x1 1 = 5.8 x2 1 = 1.8 x1 2 = 1.9 x2 2 = 5.3 v2 1 = 4.6 v1 1 = 14.3 v1 2 = 5.7 v2 2 = 11.4 q1 = 7.7 q2 = 7 w1 = 4 p1 = 11.9 p2 = 12.9 π1 = 11.4 π2 = 11.4 Now let us suppose that one consumer’s tastes are different from what we initially supposed. Initially consumer 1 was presumed to prefer wheat. Now let us presume that consumer 1 does not prefer wheat and that his or her tastes, as between wheat and wool, are about the same. The other consumer’s tastes remain the same as we thought they were initially. But consumer 1’s utility function is now assumed to be U = (x1 1) (x2 1) . There are no other changes to the parameters of the model. Endowments remain the same, as do the production functions. w2 continues to be the numeraire and it is still set at 5. 3/4 1/4 3/4 1/4 1/4 3/4 5/8 2/8 2/8 5/8 33 For the sake of brevity I have omitted the system of equations needed to perform the calculations. w1= 3.2 x1 1 = 4.2 x2 1 = 3.4 x1 2 = 2 x2 2 = 4.9 p1 = 9.9 p2 = 12.4 When consumer 1 was originally thought to have a preference for good 1, he consumed 5.8 units of it. But when we realized that he does not prefer good 1 to good 2, his consumption of good 1 was only 4.2 units and the price of good 1 was lower as well (9.9 rather than 11.9). Prices changed in this model even though there was no change in the endowments of labour and wheat, demonstrating that the value of goods can change in response to a change in preferences even if there is no change in endowments. Since consumers help to determine relative prices and, in this sense, help to create value, this analysis indicates that there can be a consumer theory of rewards dealing with contributions made by consumer wants. The analysis has not, however, determined yet whether the theory will be egalitarian or inegalitarian, which we will take up in a moment. In constructing the consumer theory of rewards, one proceeds either by considering con- sumer wants and consumer activities in abstraction from their purchasing power or by consid- ering them in conjunction with their purchasing power. The former approach would not deny that consumer wants work in conjunction with purchasing power, but would just factor out their role. Consumer wants and purchasing power can be distinguished for analytical purpos- es, on the basis of the view that purchasing power does not fully explain the consumer’s con- tribution to relative prices, because consumer wants make a relatively autonomous contribu- tion. I will consider both lines of development in this article. No attempt will be made, howev- er, to determine which one of these ways is better than the other. It seems to me that that would be a worthwhile project for anyone who wanted to further pursue the consumer theory of rewards in the future. (D) AN INITIAL POSTULATE Suppose for the moment that we consider consumer preferences in conjunction with purchas- ing power. If we do so, then it can be argued that the consumer theory of reward cannot be an egalitarian theory, because unequal purchasing power leads to unequal consumer contribution to value, which makes consumers unequally deserving of rewards. As Gary Mongiovi writes, ‘agents with greater incomes demand, and therefore induce, greater levels of production than those with lower incomes, and so would be entitled to a larger reward.’34 The unseemly logic of the theory would then be that ‘”to him that has more, more should be given.”’35 But this slogan is only implied if the analysis takes as its starting point an unequal initial distribution of income and wealth. If the starting point of the reasoning for the theory is a postulate that every- one had equal initial amounts of income and wealth, then the theory would be egalitarian in that it would posit equal shares of a portion of national income. Opening the Door to More Equality 267 34 G Mongiovi ‘Distributive Justice: An Economist’s Perspective’ (2004) 13 The Good Society 45 at 47. 35 Mongiovi ‘Distributive Justice’ (note 34 above) at 46. 2 6 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E Gary Mongiovi cautions, however, against making this postulate. ‘If the purpose of the exercise [formulating an equalitarian theory of reward] is to provide a guide to policy, we need to know how to proceed from where we now find ourselves: that is, from a position in which distribu- tion is unequal.’36 For various reasons, I think it may be necessary to construct the theory from a postulate of initial unequal income and wealth. The postulate ‘all men are equal,’ which sev- enteenth and eighteenth century liberals laid down, represented an even greater disjunction from their societies, which were even more extremely and rigidly unequal than our own, yet it still motivated historical change. To see how to proceed from where we are now, what we need to know is, not how our soci- ety would proceed, but how a just society functions. Its principles, not ours, should guide us. The critical question that needs to be addressed is this: do extreme inequalities of income nat- urally develop when economic dynamics are regulated by principles of justice? One way of find- ing the answer to this question is to inquire into whether highly unequal consumer contribu- tions arise from an initial equality of income and wealth. Such an assumption does not bias the analysis in either an egalitarian or inegalitarian direction. Suppose that consumer preferences really do make unequal contributions to value. One person with the same endowments, but greater production and consumption ambitions than another person, makes a larger contribu- tion to value that merits larger rewards. So, if consumer contributions really are unequal, they will still show up even after equal initial income and wealth is postulated. The postulate does not bias the analysis toward egalitarianism, so there should be no objection to it. But if we assume initial unequal purchasing power, it would bias the theory’s conclusions. Unequal con- tributions and rewards would follow almost automatically, so that we would not get a test of the nature of contributions. There is therefore nothing lost and much to gain from construct- ing the theory beginning with a postulate of initial equal income and wealth. The characteristics of a just economy, not of our own economy, are what we need to know if we want to know how to proceed from where we are now to a more just system. Hobbes, Locke, and Rousseau abstracted from their own societies and formulated a state of nature so that they could formulate a just society. Their own societies, fraught with a severe class system, made people appear to be very unequal. Under these circumstances, philosophers thought that they could only deter- mine if people are truly equal by abstracting from the class system that made them unequal. Once the abstraction disclosed their equality, classical liberals had a basis for condemning master-servant relations and asserting equal entitlement to rights of property. The ‘unrealistic’ abstraction from empirical class systems was precisely what they needed in order to provide guidelines for policy. Postulating an initial equal distribution of income and wealth is an analogous move with respect to the issue of equal contributions. By abstracting from prevailing sharp inequalities of purchasing power, it becomes possible to examine the logic of consumer contributions, free of the bias of unequal purchasing power, and thus to see whether consumer activities have an equal or unequal influence on the formation of value, and to act accordingly when devising distributive policy. Since the egalitarianism of the consumer theory of reward depends on a postulate of initial equal distribution of economic resources, Chris Armstrong and Peter Dietsch argue that the application of the theory in practice ‘depends on huge prior changes to the distribution of economic resources.’37 Dependence on this condition, which Dietsch believes is not likely to be achieved in the real world, 36 Mongiovi ‘Distributive Justice’ (note 34 above) at 46. 37 C Armstrong ‘Equality, Community, and the Production of Value’ (2004) European Journal of Political Theory 339 at 342; see also P Dietsch ‘Review of Ross Zucker Democratic Distributive Justice’ (2002) 14 The Review of Political Economy 397 at 398-399. renders the theory inapplicable to most real world countries. And if the theory was applied in an actual context, without equalizing the preexisting distribution of economic resources, the theory would not deliver egalitarian rewards. Because huge prior changes in the distribution of economic resources are unlikely in most places, he maintains that the theory will be strongly egalitarian only in restricted circumstances. Armstrong concludes that the social theory of rewards is not superior, as an egalitarian theory, to Rawls’s theory, which also can be egalitarian only in specific circumstances. There may be some misunderstanding over the requirements of the consumer theory of rewards. To construct the theory, which is to find out what a just economy morally entails, one has to postulate an initial equal allocation of economic resources. But to say that the theory must postulate an initial equal allocation does not mean that there must be an actual equal dis- tribution before its principles can be applied to an actual economy. The theory can be opera- tionalized without actually instituting a strictly equal distribution of income and wealth. Suppose that an egalitarian democratic regime is established by the adoption of a new set of amendments or the ratification of a new constitution altogether. Following the conclusion of the first economic period after its inauguration, just remuneration can be assessed by making a massive abstraction from contributions to economic value that come from higher or lower ini- tial endowments of income and wealth, rather than by making an actual, initial, massive, redis- tribution of economic resources. By making this abstraction from unequal initial purchasing power, the calculations of reward will necessarily be more egalitarian than they would be if the abstraction was not made. Calculating rewards this way conforms to egalitarian principles of remuneration; it does not reproduce morally questionable preexisting inequalities.38 In short, the construction of the theory requires a massive abstraction from initial high inequalities; the application of it, however, may not require an actual initial equal distribution of income and wealth. For this reason, I think that the abstraction is not unrealistic or inegali- tarian in its consequences. When Dietsch objects to the unrealism of postulating an initial equal distribution of income and wealth, his concern is not just that it is uncharacteristic of real world economies, but that its adoption in the future is unrealistic. Many analysts share the view that major states are not likely to implement extensive egalitarian redistribution in the future. The rise of American con- servatism and the collapse of communism in the former Soviet Union and Eastern Bloc lead many analysts to predict that major egalitarian changes will not occur in the future of advanced capital-based economic systems. But widespread repudiation of capitalism and acceptance of the mixed economy by populations in England and France just a few decades ago suggests that egalitarian democracy is not beyond the realm of possibility.39 Moreover, if the social welfare regime in the Netherlands and the corporatist welfare regime in Germany reduced income inequality by 30 to 40 percent in recent years, as Goodin and colleagues estimate,40 then egal- itarian norms could undergo further evolution in public opinion, leading to the eventual estab- lishment of a more egalitarian democracy in the future. Opening the Door to More Equality 269 38 One question for further research is whether one could do this in successive periods. After the second peri- od, the consumer’s purchasing power would be a combination of past unjust inequalities of income and wealth plus a reward for equal contributions that was adjusted so that initial inequalities in purchasing power were adjusted. Calculation of egalitarian rewards in the next period would depend on whether one could continue to factor out the ongoing contribution of the initial unequal endowments. If one could not, then Mongiovi is right that the theory could not be operationalized without an actual initial equal distri- bution of income and wealth devoted to consumption. 39 D Yergin & J Stanislaw The Commanding Heights (1998) at 22-25, 27. 40 R E Goodin, B Headey, R Muffels & HJ Dirven The Real Worlds of Welfare Capitalism (1999) at 185. 2 7 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E (E) SOCIAL THEORY, FORMS OF EQUAL CONTRIBUTIONS, AND EGALITARIAN ENTITLEMENTS Social theory, liberal theory, and neoclassical theory (really just an economic form of liberal the- ory) all conceive of individuals as self-determined persons, but social theory diverges from the other two theories with respect to the nature of self-determination. Liberal and neoclassical the- ories are more individualistic than social theory in that they accord social influences less weight in the formation of the self, its ends and actions. Though liberal and neoclassical theories are not entirely individualistic, they may be designated ‘individualistic’ in view of the greater weight that they place on subjective attributes, desires, and ends.41 Individualistic theories underestimate the role of social influences in the formation of the self and, therefore, also in the determination of individual actions and ends. Neoclassical theory of consumer behavior is weakened by deemphasizing social influences in the formulation of con- sumer behavior. To be sure, neoclassical economists responded to criticism of the overly sub- jectivist theory of utility maximization by developing a theory of ‘endogenous formation of preferences’ or, in other words, of social formation of preferences. But this theory does not overcome the deficiencies in the neoclassical understanding of social influence. It recognizes only arbitrary and capricious social influences (like peer pressure and bandwagon effects), neglecting more important influences flowing from system requisites which shape individuals in accord with the requirements of the system of commodity exchangers and producers. If the neoclassical theory of consumer preferences was selected for use in the theory of con- sumer rewards, the latter theory would not be egalitarian in its outcomes. The individualistic view of preferences stresses differences between consumer preferences that extend to the point of non-comparability. Individuals, understood in this way, will generate different amounts of value in the course of maximizing their utility. And those differences entitle them to very unequal amounts of rewards, on a theory of ‘dueness’ for economic contributions. But the social theory of consumer rewards which I propose is not inegalitarian, because it does not rely on the subjective theory of the consumer. The social theory of the consumer that I formulate has very different implications for con- sumer rewards. In contrast to the neoclassical theory of subjective preferences or the neoclassi- cal theory of endogenous formation of preferences I will argue that individuals have socially self-determined wants. By this I mean that individuals shape their wants, and their wants are shaped by and in accord with, the system of commodity exchangers and producers. Social analysis reveals that economic agents are subject to some of the same influences and conditions. As a result, they develop some of the same characteristics and undertake some of the same actions in creating economic value. By looking at the influences that are necessary to the exis- tence of the system and identifying the profound and systematic social influences that help to form individuals, social theory can find general equalities in individuals’ contributions to the creation of value, because the requirements of the system produce broad and deep influences affecting all alike. Using a social theory of consumer wants and desires (as well as of other attributes of the consumer), the theory of consumer rewards constitutes an egalitarian theory. Socially self-determined wants have several defining features. Although they cannot all be treated within this article, I would like to discuss some of them. To attain satisfaction from 41 By social theory I mean Hegelian social theories: GWF Hegel The Philosophy of Right (1952); DP Levine Economic Theory (1978) vol 1; and RD Winfield The Just Economy (1990). Some other kinds of social the- ories, of course, do not accept the view that individuals are self-determined. commodities produced by others, a person must want them. To want them, a person must con- stitute herself and her needs in such a manner that she can be satisfied by what other persons can provide. This kind of wants is relevant to the theory of consumer rewards because it makes a contribution to economic value. Needs that are shaped by the individual and by the system, so that they accord with what the market offers, constitute a necessary condition for the exis- tence of value. Commodities cannot have economic value, or price, unless they attract con- sumers and they cannot do the latter unless consumers are willing to shape their wants so that they can be satisfied by what the market provides. If consumers insist upon satisfying wholly subjective or psychological wants, commodity products will remain unsold and they will be valueless. Socially self-determined wants, therefore, make a contribution to value. It is, I sug- gest, a contribution people equally make. Everyone in a capital-based market system has wants of this sort and makes this sort of contribution. In this respect, consumers make an equal contribution to value. And this equal contribution makes them equally deserving of the value those help to create. Another feature of socially self-determined wants is that they are quantitatively and qualita- tively multiplied rather than fixed in kind and number. (Qualitative multiplication is a multi- plication of kinds.) Every consumer’s wants are approximately equal in that their wants are sub- ject to a quantitative and qualitative multiplication. Almost no member of a capital-based eco- nomic system is content with the biological minimum. Wants multiplied in kind and number is critical to the creation of value. In a capital-based market system, economic value is the value, not of a fixed and limited set of goods, but of a vast accumulation of commodities. The same can be said of value in a sustainable economy. The establishment of a no-(physical) growth economy, starting from the current enormous produc- tive capacity, still generates a vast amount of value, but does so without physical expansion of inputs or outputs. The vast amount of value characteristic of either a capital-based market sys- tem or a sustainable economy is impossible without consumer wants that have been quantita- tively and qualitatively multiplied. Value in a capital-based market system is capable of ongo- ing expansion through increases either in the physical or non-physical amounts of inputs and outputs. Expansion of value may also be possible in a sustainable economy, but it takes the form of growth without increases in physical magnitudes of inputs and outputs. Expansion of value either in a capitalist economy or a sustainable economy would be impossible if the wants of consumers were fixed in kind and number. Multiplied wants provide the motivational spur for the multiplication of commodities and the expansion of value. Multiplication of wants is, therefore, essential to the existence of value as self-expanding value. Since every consumer’s wants are subject to a quantitative and qualitative multiplication, each person is in this sense equally responsible for the existence of economic value. Corresponding to this form of equal responsibility for value, all consumers are equally respon- sible for the value that is generated by this kind of equality. Though they are not entitled to equal amounts of the total national income, because there are, in addition to their equal con- tributions, different contributions to value, such as in the amount and kind of their productive activities. The quantitative and qualitative multiplication of wants is not something that varies with consumers’ incomes, so its contribution to value does not differ depending with different con- sumers’ incomes. The quantitative and qualitative multiplication of wants is excited by expo- sure to the manifold products of the division of labour, rather than being a function of indi- viduals’ incomes. It forms a motivational bedrock for the multiplication of commodities and for the expansion of value that is relatively independent of differences between consumers’ Opening the Door to More Equality 271 2 7 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E incomes. While a person’s purchasing power may limit his or her effective demand, that pur- chasing power will not be translated into an actual purchase unless the person’s wants have been subject to quantitative and qualitative multiplication. The equality among persons’ wants with respect to the quantitative and qualitative multiplication of wants makes them equally entitled to the part of value that is due to this form of wants. (F) INDIRECT CONTRIBUTIONS AND INDIRECT ENTITLEMENTS Another form of contribution that consumers make toward the creation of economic value is more indirect than the two described above and it deals with a different aspect of socially self- determined wants. A consumer can indirectly contribute to the creation of economic value by influencing the preferences of other consumers. As already noted, consumer preferences can affect prices. By the same token, an individual who influences other consumers’ preferences plays an indirect role in their contribution to the creation of value. This influence can qualify as a contribution itself, despite being an indirect factor. If consumer preferences can contribute to the creation of value, then individual influences that help to form their preferences can also be contributions to the creation of value, though more indirectly. The reason for this is that almost any human contribution to the creation of value, direct or indirect, warrants remuner- ation on a principle of dueness for economic contributions. If we grant that social influences upon consumer preferences can contribute to the creation of value, then the question arises whether it has egalitarian implications when incorporated into the theory of consumer rewards. This depends upon whether individuals contribute equally or unequally to the formation of consumer preferences. To answer this question, we have to explore the relevant social influences. For this purpose we may focus on the social formation of the following feature of consumer wants: the fact that they are quantitatively and qualita- tively multiplied rather than fixed and limited. At first it seems unlikely that individuals have equal influence upon consumer preferences in this respect. A large advertising agency, such as J Walter Thompson, presumably has greater im- pact upon the multiplication of consumer wants than the average individual does. Yet I will argue that the average individual exerts a profound, though less obvious, influence upon the multiplication of kinds and numbers of consumer preferences, And I will argue, further, that, in this process, she or he has equal formative influence upon other consumers’ multiplicity of wants. The multiplication of wants that is significantly responsible for the multiplication and expansion of value arises within the social process of formation of wants. By way of illustration consider the formation of the desire for a Mercedes Benz. Influences which help to create this sort of want are systemic. Although advertisers affect the market for Mercedes, they may not be the sole or primary influence on the desire for these cars. The interest of the wealthy in Mercedes presumes the existence of a society with a keen interest in automobiles. Mercedes provide their owners a status symbol, which impresses rich, poor, and middle class alike. But the status symbol that it provides is so ubiq- uitous because the great bulk of consumers value cars. The great car culture of the United States accounts more for the interest in Mercedes cars than an advertiser could. This car culture is not just an epiphenomenon of automobile advertisements, but a way of life embraced by the great bulk of consumers in the US. Interest in cars is excited by exposure to them in the neighborhood, by neigh- borhood talk about cars, and by cultural practices regarding cars. Ultimately it is due to the system of consumers because neighborhood talk and practices are influenced by interactions between peo- ple of different neighborhoods. Interactions between members of the system of commodity exchang- ers spread the virtues of cars far and wide. This case suggests that the multiplication of wants occurs through the interactions of a system of individuals. Because the system of commodity exchangers is profoundly responsible for multiplying the kinds and numbers of preferences, credit for this is spread equally among individuals. They are equally system-members and it is as system-members that they have their most profound influence. On a principle of remuneration for economic contributions, the account of the indirect formation of the multiplication of the kinds and number of wants supports an equal distribution of the value generated by the action of these socially self-determined prefer- ences upon prices. The argument that individuals have an equally strong mutual influence on each others’ pref- erences — and that this justifies a certain distributive equality — is ‘highly speculative’ and ‘less interesting,’ according to Peter Dietsch, because it ‘depends on equal income and wealth to start with,’ which is an ‘unrealistic premise.’42 I have argued above that it is not unrealistic or unwar- ranted to postulate initial equal income and wealth. If that argument is correct, it follows that it is not unrealistic or uninteresting to argue that individuals have an equally strong mutual influence on others’ preferences. Deutsch does not doubt that there would be relatively equal formative influence on preferences if there were an initial equal allocation of income and wealth. If this premise is realistic — relative to the nature of a just economy — then the rest of the characteristics that I have ascribed to this order are not highly speculative. Equally strong mutual influence on individual preferences would follow and equal indirect entitlements for value created thereby would also follow. (G) ANOTHER FORM OF EQUAL CONTRIBUTION Consumers have another equal feature that contributes to the value of commodities. One of the most important causes of the subsistence of value is the process of ongoing circulation of com- modities and money. I argue that consumers equally accept the system goal of ongoing circu- lation of commodities and money and that, by doing so, they make equal contributions to the subsistence of value through the circuit, which entitles them equally to shares of part of the value sustained and expanded by this process. According to neoclassical economics, consumers are preference maximizers. That is their only goal. Contrary to this view, Adam Smith asserted that all individuals have a goal of having money at hand.43 The goal of having money at hand has no meaning or purpose in itself, but derives sig- nificance from the fact that it is necessary for the circulation to continue. Therefore, the goal of having money at hand is, inferably, a tacit acceptance of the system goal of ongoing circulation of commodities and money. General acceptance of this goal reflects centuries of accumulated expe- rience with the circulation of commodities and money, and societal acceptance of the goal repre- sents a tacit recognition that payment for produced goods is a necessary condition for the ongo- ing circulation of commodities and the reproduction and expansion of capital. Moreover, the exchange cannot be written off as reflecting ideological hegemony or domination, because the cir- culation of capital is necessary even in a socialist market system. Unlike the neoclassical theory of consumer behavior in which preference maximization appears as subjective choice, self-seeking in accord with the goal of ongoing circulation of capital is a form of social self-determination. The individual has this goal through a social self-determination. Because individuals subsist within a system of commodity circulation, no one will give the indi- Opening the Door to More Equality 273 42 Dietsch ‘Review’ (note 37 above) at 398-399. 43 A Smith The Wealth of Nations (1937) at 22. 2 7 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E vidual anything economically valuable without receiving valuable consideration in exchange. The individual assimilates a goal of ongoing circulation because he or she must do so in order to sub- sist within a social process dependent upon ongoing circulation of commodities. Self-seeking in accord with the goal of ongoing circulation is one of the individual’s most important contributions to the subsistence of value through the circuit, and in this sense to the creation of value. Patterns of accountability for this kind of self-seeking therefore relate directly to the problem of determining individuals’ dueness for value contributions, that is, for determin- ing the amount of value that should be distributed to them because its creation is due to them. The fact that the individual has a goal of ongoing circulation of commodities is partly due to every other member of the process. As determinants of her having this goal, they are also a fun- damental source of her contribution to the value of commodities, for her actions in accord with this goal contribute to the subsistence of value and, therefore, to the creation of value. These other persons, therefore, have an indirect entitlement to a share of the value that accrues to her in the course of her socially self-determined self-seeking. This makes property a right to some significant equalization of value. In what way do they all contribute to the fact that she has and pursues a goal of ongoing cir- culation? When the individual approaches the world of commodity exchange with the intent of acquiring a desired good, no one will give it to her without receiving another good or money in return, because each knows that he can’t survive and flourish in a process of ongoing circu- lation unless he makes this stipulation. And this is an exceptionally strong inducement to the consumer to have a goal of having money at hand — the prime condition for the ongoing cir- culation of commodities and money. In order for this indirect contribution to be an equal contribution (deserving of equal rewards), the influence of each other person upon the consumer would have to be equal. Is the contribution that others make to her having the goal of having money at hand an equal con- tribution? The fact that a wealthier person declines to turn over goods without consideration is no more or less responsible for her assimilation of said goal than the fact that a poorer person makes a similar stipulation for entering into exchange with her. It is clear, then, that everyone else has a relatively equal responsibility for the fact that the individual has a goal of ongoing circulation of commodities and money. The people exercising this indirect influence have an indirect entitlement to equal shares of part of the value that accrues to the subject in the course of her market activities, specifically, the part of the value due to their indirect influence. This has implications for Spragens’ contention that purchasing power is the major consideration in considering a consumer’s contributions to value. The indirect influence of the consumer on other consumers just discussed does not depend on differential purchasing power. (H) DISTRIBUTIVE EFFECTS The social theory of rewards for contributions yields a right to an equal portion of part of the income that accrues to every other person in the course of her or his market activities. At this point in the development of the theory, I have not yet fixed the redistributable portion, except to say that it is clearly a substantial amount, in view of the enormous contribution that consumers make to the creation of value. We can get a sense of the theory’s potential distributive effects by con- sidering how inequality is affected by its adoption in two sorts of economies, one with a less unequal economy, another with a more unequal economy. Assume that the size of the redistrib- utable portion is 10 percent of each person’s income. This means that every citizen shall pay 10 percent of her or his income and that 10 percent of the income of every person will be distributed in equal amounts to every person. As the first half of Table 1 illustrates, this kind of redistribu- tion can be effective in promoting equality in the less unequal economy. As a result of this redis- tribution, the income of the poorest 5 percent rises by 115 percent, the income of the next 15 per- cent of the population rises by 35.5 percent, the income of the second quintile rises by 12.2 per- cent, the income of the third quintile rises by 3.2 percent, while the fourth quintile experiences minimal reduction in income (only -1.4 percent), the next 15 percent of the people experience a moderate reduction in income of -4.5 percent, and the income of the richest 5 percent declines by -7.7 percent. Under this plan, a substantial increase in income equality is achieved at small cost to the middle class and without severe reduction in the position of the top 5 percent of the popula- tion. Only 20 percent of the population incurs noticeable loss of income and it is not a large loss compared to the very considerable gains they get from social cooperation. Opening the Door to More Equality 275 TABLE 1 DISTRIBUTIVE CONSEQUENCES OF THE SOCIAL THEORY OF CONSUMER REWARDS, ASSUMING A 10% TAX* Distributive effects in a less unequal economy Bottom Next Next Next Next Next Top Percentile 5% 15% 20% 20% 20% 15% 5% Share of Total Income 0.4% 3.3% 9.0% 15.1% 23.3% 27.3% 21.6% 100.0% Number of Persons 1 3 4 4 4 3 1 20 Total Income 4 33 90 151 233 273 216 $1,000 10% Tax 0.4 3.3 9 15.1 23.3 27.3 21.6 $100 Redistributed on Per Capital Basis 5 15 20 20 20 15 5 $100 Income after Tax and Transfer 8.6 44.7 101 155.9 229.7 260.7 199.4 $1,000 Percentage Increase in Income 115.0% 35.5% 12.2% 3.2% -1.4% -4.5% -7.7% Top 5%/Bottom 5% (pre-tax) 54 Top 5%/Bottom 5% (post-tax and transfer) = 23 Distributive effects in a more unequal economy Bottom Next Next Next Next Next Top Percentile 5% 15% 20% 20% 20% 15% 5% Share of Total Income 0.2% 2.0% 5.4% 9.1% 26.9% 31.5% 24.9% 100.0% Number of Persons 1 3 4 4 4 3 1 20 Total Income 2.0 20.0 54.0 91.0 269.0 315.0 249.0 $1,000 10% Tax 0.2 2.0 5.4 9.1 26.9 31.5 24.9 $100 Redistributed on Per Capital Basis 5 15 20 20 20 15 5 $100 Income after Tax and Transfer 6.8 33.0 68.6 101.9 262.1 298.5 229.1 $1,000 Percentage Increase in Income 240.0% 65.0% 27.0% 12.0% -2.6% -5.2% -8.0% Top 5%/Bottom 5% (pre-tax) 125 Top 5%/Bottom 5% (post-tax and transfer) = 34 * I am grateful to KS Sastry for providing the first half of this table: Distributive Effects of the Social Theory of Rewards in a Less Unequal Economic Society. 2 7 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E In the more unequal economy, the implementation of the egalitarian right achieves even more dramatic improvement in income equality. The lower three quintiles all make substantial increases of income, with the bottom 5 percent receiving a whopping 240 percent increase in their income, while only the highest quintile suffers substantially decreased incomes (-8 percent for top 5 percent and -5.2 percent for the next 15 percent), which does not seem large next to the benefits that they derive from social cooperation. III Social Ethics of Economic Community (A) INTRODUCTION The ethics of economic community can also help us to open the door to more equality. The central idea of this ethics is as follows: when a number of individuals are united for the pur- suit of some end that they hold in common, they should be able to share in the attainment of that end. Although the ethics of economic community is controversial, this main theme is not particularly problematic. It has strong intuitive appeal, garnering support from people of diverse ideologies. Various theorists, ranging from classical liberals (Locke and Kant, whom some libertarians venerate)44 to social theorists (Hegel and Charles Taylor) give their analyt- ical support to it. The ethics of economic community faces other difficulties. These problems relate to the appropriateness or relevance of communal ethics to capital-based market systems. It is quite clear that an association would have to be a community before it could qualify for regulation by the ethics of community. This is because community is the moral basis that invokes the dis- tributive rule of the ethics of community. The contention that everyone should share equally in the ends of association is without foundation if the association is not a community. The com- munal requirement for applying the ethics of community seems to be an insuperable barrier to applying it to capital-based market systems, for these systems are not communities in the view of most analysts. Some theorists point out sub-communities within the modern economy. Others point to the surrounding community in the form of a political system with common ends. Still others say the economy is contained within a communal ‘social capsule.’45 But not even the most ardent communitarians like Amitai Etzioni claim that capital-based market sys- tems are communities. Scholars understand the capital-based market system as a competitive, rather than commu- nal, system. Some tend to see it as atomistic. Others prefer to say it is individualistic. Still oth- ers qualify its individualism, saying the market and the division of labour are conditions of interdependence rather than of pure self-reliance. But even when qualified by interdependence, scholars do not generally regard the capital-based market economy as a community. Recognition of interdependence does not lead them to pronounce it a community. Most scholars who position themselves on the matter maintain that market interdependence is not communal because it lacks the common action for common ends essential to community.46 Understanding the economy as a condition of individualistic interdependence rather than of 44 R Nozick Anarchy, State, and Utopia (1974) at 32, 337 fn 4. 45 A Etzioni The Moral Dimension (1988) at 212, 199-216. 46 C Armstrong ‘Equality’ (note 37 above) at 343; V Chibber ‘Individualism, Community, and Distributive Justice’ (2004) 13 The Good Society 62 at 63-65. communal interdependence leaves scholars indisposed toward egalitarian rules of distribution of income, because they can’t see the communal basis for invoking such rules. While capital-based market systems are evidently not fully communal, no one has proved that they do not contain a dimension of community on a systemwide scale. The existence of this dimension remains an open question. This possibility deserves further study, because it ful- fills the prerequisites for applying communal ethics of distribution to these systems. Community is more often contrasted with markets than identified with them, because it usu- ally involves some sort of central direction or authority through which people implement their common purposes, whereas the market is composed of decentralized exchange relations though which people pursue alternate goals.47 Hierarchical medieval community, twentieth century communism, and liberal political community exemplify communities with central authority. Community can, however, take a decentralized form, such as general agreement or common character. So the market’s decentralized character does not preclude its having a dimension of community. From this we can learn something more about the kind of object that the search for economic community is looking for. It seeks a dimension of community within a decentral- ized system. For that to exist, it would have to be possible for a system of individuals to engage in common action for common ends through decentralized interactions. There is an intuitive basis for the notion of a dimension of community within capital-based market systems. As individuals compete in the modern market economy, they simultaneously stitch together something of a community by engaging in common actions for certain common ends. Each one of them is involved in doing things for other people that they would otherwise have to do for themselves, and that meets the definition of common action. Arguably, all eco- nomic agents have a common goal of preserving and expanding capital, because all of the goods and services that they desire hinge on the ongoing circuit of money and commodities, that is, the circuit of capital. The common actions sustaining the circuit of capital are generated by socially influenced but individually willed actions. An element of cooperation arises between firms because they have to adjust their production processes to what other firms provide and need. Though opposed in a number of ways, capital and labour also unite to produce and gain portions of social wealth. Mutual adjustment is required for joint production. Labourers and managers of capital acquire skills and pattern their work for the efficient production of goods and capital. Moreover, since profits depend on sales, production and consumption are interrelated as well. While producers orient output toward the satisfaction of consumer wants, they also shape those wants by adver- tising their products and by other means. This intuition suggests that capital-based market systems have a communal dimension. If so, this kind of system has the qualification for being regulated by the ethics of community, to some significant extent. Because this ethics morally warrants equal distribution of relevant resources among community members, capital-based market systems should be subject to this rule to the extent that they are communities. From the intuitive account just given, it is apparent that individual actions and ends in the economy have an inter-subjective inner structure. By that I mean the inner composition of the person changed in response to the requirements for self-seeking under conditions of mutual dependence. For example, labour acquires skills and patterns her work for the efficient pro- duction of goods and capital, because she cannot gain a share of wealth unless she unites with Opening the Door to More Equality 277 47 On the nature of markets, see CE Lindblom Politics and Markets (1977) at 33-51. 2 7 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E capital in a process of commodity production. The inter-subjective inner structure of the per- son is noteworthy because it constitutes a nexus between individual action and ends and the actions and ends of others. Instead of being substantive, that is, independent and self-existent, individual action and ends, therefore, are dependent parts of common action and ends. By way of illustration, the nature of the skills acquired, the labour performed, and the education under- taken — are all characteristic of the inter-subjective inner structure of the worker, whose labour forms common action with other workers and with the owners and managers of capital. And only insofar as it constitutes common action does it constitute productive action. Neoclassical economic theory does not grasp the dimension of community in the economy, partially because it passes over the internal changes which individuals make in response to the requirements for self-seeking within the circuit of capital. As mentioned above, neoclassical theory subscribes to conception of the self as having a subjective, rather than inter-subjective, structure of the self. On this basis it is not able to grasp the nexus between individual action and ends and common action and ends, which also renders it incapable of recognizing the exis- tence of economic community. Instead it renders a stylized portrait of the economy as a highly individualized process, with market outcomes resulting from the choices of largely self-deter- mined decision makers (producers, consumers and resource holders).48 (B) COMMUNITY AMONG CONSUMERS AND PRODUCERS The next stage of argument is to elabourate upon the preceding sketch. To demonstrate a dimension of community in the economy, one has to show that — despite the existence of dif- ferent categories of economic agents — the members of the economy share some attributes, actions, and ends. I will argue that consumers, producers, owners of capital, and managers of it share some fundamental attributes in common and they engage in common action toward a common end, even though they belong to different categories of economic agents. To begin with, let us consider the relationship between consumers and producers. According to neoclassical economic theory, consumers and producers hold alternative behav- ioral goals: preference maximization and profit maximization. The engagement of consumers and producers in separate actions in pursuit of alternative goals would appear to refute the contention that they engage in common action toward a common end. But does it really? While consumers and producers pursue alternative goals through separate actions, could they not also be engaged at the same time in other actions toward other ends with communal features? The neoclassical portrayal elides these correlative communal actions and ends, but they can be restored to view. Preference maximization and profit maximization each has a correlative action that reveals common action among consumers and producers. A producer does not just engage in profit maximization. She also produces useful and desirable items for the benefit of consumers. A con- sumer, meanwhile, does not just engage in preference maximization. He also pays money for the useful or desirable objects acquired from producers. Because profit maximization includes the production of use-values, it is designed to give consumers what they want. Likewise, because preference maximization includes the payment of money, it is designed to give produc- ers what they want. Seen in relation to their correlative actions, preference maximization and profit maximization meet the qualification for common action in markets. Common action in markets is defined by the conjunction of two sorts of actions: (a) an 48 Debreu Theory of Value (note 31 above). action by one person for another person that the second person would have to do for himself if the first person did not do for him and (b) an action by the second person for the first per- son that the first person would have to do for himself if the second person did not do it for him. Payment of money by the consumer to the producer and production of goods by the producer for the consumer unite preference maximization and profit maximization in common action. These two categories of maximizing behaviors, therefore, cannot be understood simply as alter- native behaviors that separate consumer behavior from producer behavior. Granting that consumers and producers engage in common actions, what about common ends? In neoclassical economics, the market system is defined as a mechanism for the allocation of scare resources between alternative ends. By definitional fiat, common ends are precluded. A better place to look for ends, I suggest, is in the process of circulation of capital. The owner of capital seeks to exchange money for commodities. She then combines them as productive capital for the production of commodities for sale. The various actions of the capi- tal owner have a common underlying goal: to acquire more economic value. Taken together these actions constitute an expansion of value, but the acquisition of value is not a final goal, it is just a means of renewing the circuit. It returns the capital owner to her starting point, which leads to multiple repetitions of the circuit. Production, then, is not simply production, but part of a larger circulatory process. Consumer purchases help owners and managers to complete the circuit of the firm’s capital. Because consumer payment is a necessary link that completes the producer’s circuit, the two constitute common action. Consumer behavior is not ordinarily conceived of in this way. Consumers are said to make independent decisions about the kinds and quantities of goods they buy. These decisions may in turn injure the rejected producers rather than complete the circuit of their capital. For this reason, consumer behavior is generally not understood as action taken in common with producers. But consumers would have to perform the behavior of profit max- imization if producers did not do it. It is for this reason that they induce producers to become profit maximizers by making profit maximizers better off than profit minimizers. Producers freely accept these action directives from consumers because they can become better off that way. Since producer activities are made to serve consumer goals through inducements offered by consumers, profit maximization forms a common activity with preference maximization, not simply an alternative to it. Up to this point, we have considered bilateral relationships between the consumer and the circuit of individual capital. But in order to demonstrate a dimension of community on a sys- temwide scale, we have to identify a broader pattern of common action and ends than just bilat- eral ones. Every consumer does not relate only to the firms from which she makes her pur- chases. The capital of each firm, from which she purchases, is directly or indirectly related to that of other firms. The interdependence of producers is systematic. Exchange links them with every other owner of capital. As a result, every consumer interrelates with those other firms and, therefore, with the system of circulation. The systemic interdependence of individual cir- cuits implies a correspondingly systemic scope of common action within the economy. Consumers and producers have alternative ends, as neoclassical theory maintains, in the sense that consumer 1 may not want good X produced by producer 2 and seeks instead good Y produced by producer 3. This condition of alternative ends precludes the existence of com- prehensive community within the economy. But it does not preclude the existence of a commu- nity overarching the pursuit of these alternative particular ends. Relatively independent actions and ends are subsumed under more general common actions and ends: the ongoing process of circulation of capital. Although consumer 1 purchases producer 3’s product, rather than produc- Opening the Door to More Equality 279 2 8 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E er 2’s product, he nonetheless shares an overarching common end: the preservation of producers’ capital. This goal glimmers through the consumer’s actions when he pays money for goods received, because such payment is a general need of all producers, not just of producer 3. (C) COMMUNITY AND EQUAL SHARES OF PART OF NATIONAL INCOME According to classical liberal theory, people unite for the sake of attaining a certain common goal: the goal of living under conditions where each person can define and pursue his or her own ends. These conditions are the conditions of right or ethically valid freedom. In other words, people unite in civil society because it is their common will to live under conditions of right. In the classical liberal theory, the presence of community with respect to living under con- ditions of right is the moral basis for the equal entitlement to rights. It entitles every member of civil society to the right of property. Property is a matter of right, not just a matter of the good, because it is the freedom of the person to define and pursue her own ends in relation to and over external things. Classical liberal theory does not, however, maintain that people are entitled to equal amounts of property. While defending a communal basis for the equal right to property it denies a com- munal basis for the right to equal amounts of property. There is a union with respect to the gen- eral conditions needed for the free choice of ends, but not a union with respect to the amounts of goods a person should have. The sphere in which goods are pursued, which we call an econ- omy, is characterized as a disunified multitude. ‘Men have different views of the … ends of hap- piness,’ Kant states, ‘so that as far as happiness is concerned, their will cannot be brought under any common principle.’49 The disunified multitude with respect to the pursuit of the good can- not supply the necessary communal basis for a right to equal amounts of property. Owing to the absence of economic community, ‘the utmost inequality of the mass in the degree of its pos- sessions’ is admissible, Kant maintains. 50 The classical liberal principle of the distribution of property is mistaken, in my view, because it is based on a one-sided account of the economy. When Kant ascribes unqualified disunity to the economy, he neglects the presence of a dimension of community, which can supply com- munal basis for equal distribution of part of national income. He believes community is limit- ed to what may be called a procedural community, where citizens are agreed that everyone should be able to choose his or her own ends. But citizens also agree on a substantive end, the goal of creating and acquiring wealth. Their common will to create and acquire wealth estab- lishes a substantive community in the economy which morally grounds a right to equal shares of part of national income. Contrary to the view that everyone in civil society seeks wealth, it is sometimes argued that some people just seek subsistence and other people just seek comfort. But most members of cap- ital-based market systems exhibit larger numbers and kinds of needs than this view suggests. Most people in these systems do not seek mere biological subsistence. There are few who seek to subsist on a biological cocktail of the minimally necessary nutrients for survival. Even with respect to typical subsistence goods like food, the lower strata have preferences, for example between different sorts of bread. And their wants are not usually limited to classical subsistence goods. They manifest preferences for various kinds of processed foods and other goods. Most 49 I Kant ‘On the Common Saying: “This May be True in Theory, But it Does not Apply in Practice”’ in Hans Riess (ed) Kant’s Political Writings (1970) 61 at 73-74. 50 Kant ‘On the Common Saying’ (note 49 above) at 75. people in a capital-based market system clearly have a wide range of needs: needs for televi- sions, radios, a telephone, McDonald’s hamburgers, CDs, tapes, expensive sneakers and other fashionable garb, among other things. Each person has a range of wants for things beyond fixed needs for subsistence, but he or she may differ from other persons in some of his or her specific preferences. The fact that some of the wants that people have differ from those of other persons does not however confirm Kant’s view that people differ in the ends of happiness or that there cannot be any economic community. The range of wants just mentioned is not encompassed by needs for the naturally occurring surplus of nature or by the products of limited commodity production. It entails wants that are wants for social wealth, for a vast accumulation of commodities produced by a system of wealth. Reflective of the need for wealth, most people in the United States do not engage in production of use-values for self-consumption, which would supply a much more restricted range of goods. Rather, they seek a money wage that gives them command over part of the world of commodities, that is, over social wealth. Since the members of a capital-based market system all seek wealth in this sense, there is a community of ends among them, includ- ing the lower strata. Against the claimed existence of economic community, one might argue that people pursue a great variety of different ends, not just the end of wealth. You use your wealth to buy a house because you like suburban living; I rent an apartment because I prefer urban living. But the goal of seeking wealth permeates every other goal of economic agents, whatever else they seek. Both an apartment and a house are forms of social wealth, bought and built with particles of social wealth; so they are not merely forms of natural shelter. The common goal of wealth, permeating different particular ends, substantiates a claim that a dimension of community pervades the economy. To be sure, many people are content with a comfortable living and they may recoil from the garishness and materialism of those they view as seekers of wealth. But what many people call a desire for comfort is really a desire for wealth, properly understood. The desire for wealth is not best understood as a desire for a limousine or a penthouse. It should be grasped as the sort of desire that has been multiplied in kind and number and that cannot be satisfied without a social production process capable of producing an immense accumulation of commodities. Let us take a look at the seemingly modest requirement for ‘comfort.’ In the United States today, the desire for comfort encompasses desires for things like automobiles, refrigerators, toaster ovens, televisions, stereo equipment, processed foods of manifold varieties, microwave ovens, clothes of considerable variety, furniture of various sorts, travel vacations, restaurants, computers, books, leisure for study or recreation, college and graduate education, movies, inter- net connections, highly advanced medical treatment. But these are in no sense modest wants, wants that can adequately be deemed ‘comfort.’ Satisfying wants like these requires products that result from a prodigious system of wealth generation, whose products are parcels of social wealth. The fact that an immense accumula- tion of commodities is needed to satisfy quantitatively and qualitatively multiplied wants shows how little the term ‘comfort’ conveys about the average person’s objectives in economic socie- ty. Wealth is, quite clearly, the only appropriate term to designate the amount and diversity of stuff under consideration. The desire for this, which is pervasive in capital-based market sys- tems, is the desire for wealth. So the desire for wealth is a common desire. Since everyone in a capital-based market system seeks wealth in the sense just described, a community of economic ends exists within the economic system. The dimension of economic community indicated by commonalities in economic ends supplies a communal basis for demanding equal distribution of part of national income. But it does not require equalization Opening the Door to More Equality 281 2 8 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E of all national income, because the economy is not entirely community, for although everyone seeks wealth they also seek different particular use-values. If, as Kant argued, community with regard to conditions for choosing one’s own ends equally entitles members to the right of prop- erty, then union for the pursuit and acquisition of wealth must entitle them to equal distribu- tion of part of national income, proportionate to the extent of community. The members of a capital-based market system are united with respect to more than just employment or a minimally decent income. They are united with respect to a larger share of the economic resources of society. They are united for the sake of the preservation and expansion of the capital of the firm and of the system in its entirety. Given the interdependence of indi- vidual pursuits of wealth, there is a unity among them with respect to all of the capital wealth of the nation that is used for consumption. Labour has an interest, not only in a wage, but in all of the capital wealth of the firm and of the nation. Consumers seek not only to satisfy pref- erences but also to satisfy a multiplication of kinds and numbers of preferences, so they have a common desire for wealth. Analysis of their wants revealed that they have not only a common denominator in wanting at least a minimally decent level of consumption, but also a common denominator with respect to the rest of consumption. This common denominator consists in the quantitative and qualitative multiplication of all consumers’ wants, which implies that they have a common desire for wealth. The community of ends is, therefore, much broader than the- orists of the welfare state recognize. The consumers’ goal of seeking wealth cannot be achieved without their participation in a system of commodity exchange and production based on capi- tal, which has a dimension of common action, since individual circuits of capital are intercon- nected. Individual action in pursuit of wealth therefore exhibits a dimension of common action. The multiplication of wants unites consumers with producers in the circulation process, because this process continues and expands the circulation of capital. Since economic agents are united with respect to many more economic resources than mod- ern liberal theory realizes, they must, correspondingly, have an equal entitlement to a larger part of economic resources than such theory posits. The unity of capital owners, labourers, and con- sumers for the sake of the creation and acquisition of capital gives every member an equal enti- tlement to an equal share of part of the national income devoted to purposes of consumption. They are not just entitled to employment or subsistence, since their unity is not limited to the common pursuit of employment or subsistence. Given the interdependence between individual pursuits of wealth, there is a unity between them with respect to all of the capital wealth of the nation used for consumption. Claims based on membership in this sort of union extend to all of the capital wealth of the nation that is directed toward consumption and that is created by community. This membership does not, however, justify a strict equalization of income, because the overarching unity of economic actors includes a lot of relatively independent action for somewhat separate ends. (D) DO PEOPLE BUY CHOCOLATE BECAUSE THEY LIKE IT? The notion of a common goal of acquiring and consuming wealth is ‘very generalized’ and ‘insubstantial,’ according to Chris Armstrong.51 The alleged dimension of community is there- fore also insubstantial and it cannot supply the moral warrant for egalitarian regulation of income distribution in capital-based market systems, he argues. Furthermore, the desire for 51 Armstrong ‘Equality’ (note 37 above) at 343. wealth is unreal. ‘Personally, I usually buy chocolate because I like it,’ he says, not because I seek wealth.52 Intuitive appeal is, admittedly, all on the side of Armstrong’s point. And it would seem to form a basis for a powerful critique of the ethics of economic community. If Armstrong is right in suggesting that people buy chocolate simply because they like it, then there is no common desire for wealth, in which case a major foundation for the theory of economic community is lost, along with the redistributive ethics of community that is built on top of it. Because the argument for the existence of community hinges on the existence of a common desire for wealth Armstrong’s critique needs to be considered. For this reason we find ourselves is the rather awk- ward position of having to undertake a rather extended excursus on chocolate. Although Armstrong has intuition on his side, the proper study of needs in capital-based markets requires abstraction. The issue calls to mind Adam Smith’s statement that one can only appreciate the divided nature of manufacturing through theoretical analysis, because ‘we can seldom see more, at any one time, than those employed in a single branch.’53 In contrast, con- sumer goals, as Armstrong conceives of them, are entirely concrete and particular, devoid of any abstract or general feature substantial enough to constitute a community. Armstrong’s point that people buy chocolate because they like it is seemingly self-evident, but it actually reduces a complex social phenomenon to a simple datum and underestimates the importance of the abstract and general features of desire, which form a real component of its nature, just as the division of labour is an essential aspect of labour. The desire for chocolate or the want for chocolate is an instance of the desire for wealth rather than the natural need for subsistence. The need for subsistence is a need for food, clothing, and shelter in their most basic forms, as required for survival. In contrast, the desire for wealth may be defined as a desire that has been multiplied in two ways: it is multiplied, qualitatively, in terms of the kinds of things that individuals want to consume and, quantitatively, in regard to the amounts of things they want. There is no assignable limit upon the kinds and numbers of things that people who desire wealth can want, whereas people who seek subsistance seek a fixed and limited set of substances. Like the desire for other objects of wealth, the desire for chocolate has been multiplied in kind and number and it continues to increase without apparent limit. Total US consumption of chocolate stood at 3.3 billion pounds in 1999 and per capita con- sumption rose above 11.9 pounds.54 At these levels, the desire for chocolate has clearly been multiplied in amount and it is widespread too: 84% of households consume it, 72% more than once a week.55 By the 1980s Hershey’s found enough desire there to sell 25 million kisses a day.56 The kinds of desires for chocolate have also been subject to multiplication. The desire for chocolate candy has been diversified into desires for solid chocolate, solid chocolate with inclusions, enrobed or molded chocolate with bakery-product centre (eg, chocolate covered wafers), enrobed or molded with candy, fruit, nut, or granola centre (eg chocolate covered cher- ries), panned (eg chocolate-covered raisins), and assortments of the above types or others. Between World War I and World War II, more than 30,000 varieties of chocolate bars were Opening the Door to More Equality 283 52 Armstrong ‘Equality’ (note 37 above) at 343. 53 Smith (note 43 above) at 4. 54 R Lopez Chocolate: The Nature of Indulgence (2002) at 109. 55 RM Rees ‘Bite-Sized Marketing: Candy Bars’ in A Szogyi (ed) Chocolate: Food of the Gods (1997) 125 at 128; The Chocolate Market (2001) at 31 Web publication by MarketResearch.com Academic: www.aca- demic.marketresearch.com/product/print/default.asp?. 56 M Morton and F Morton Chocolate: An Illustrated History (1986) at 94. 2 8 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E introduced.57 Desire for chocolate candy was subsequently differentiated into desires for choco- lates distinguished by size and packaging, as well as by seasonal and non-seasonal characteris- tics. It has been multiplied by differentiating it into desires for four categories of chocolate prod- ucts: chocolate candy, chocolate chips/baking chocolate, powdered cocoa mixes, and chocolate syrup/dessert toppings. It has also been differentiated and multiplied into desires for many other product types that contain chocolate but whose primary definition is not chocolate, such as cake mixes, frostings, and cake decorations; ice cream, puddings, and other deserts, and cocoa-fla- vored cereals. In fact, the desire for chocolate has been distinguished into so many types that it would take more than five pages to list the top brands and products of selected marketers in the US chocolate market alone. A single commercial supplier lists 2,000 types of chocolate.58 With the multiplication of kinds and numbers of desires for chocolate, the desire for chocolate has the character of a desire for wealth. The number and kinds of chocolate products are wealth in the sense that they clearly form part of a vast accumulation of commodities, which is what wealth is. And the desire for them is a desire for particles of social wealth. The kinds and numbers of these desires are too great to be classified as either subsistence wants or comfort. Another feature of a desire for wealth that the desire for chocolate exhibits is that it expands and increases. ‘Per capita consumption of chocolate candy has risen steadily over the past few years, growing 13% between 1994 and 1998, from 10.8 pounds to 12.2 pounds’.59 New desires keep arising in relation to new products that have been innovated. In 1999-2000, Hershey’s alone introduced nine new products: Kit Kat Big Kat, line extensions to Hershey’s bites — York Peppermint, etc — Novelty Dr Seuss’s How the Grinch Stole Christmas packages, Whoppers, Cinnamon Chips, syrup in Hershel the Cow-shaped bottles, and Health Sundae Syrup, and Fudge Cookie Crunch Shell topping. Twenty percent of ‘Hershey’s recent sales come from new products’.60 It is in the nature of wealth that it expands and increases. It is self-expanding value, rather than just value that gets reproduced at an arbitrarily assigned level. As an expanding desire, the desire for chocolate has the quality of the desire for particles of wealth. We can also see that the desire for chocolate is a desire for wealth when we look at the process by which this desire is formed. Ideas play a role in the expansion of a person’s desires, but these ideas may not all originate within the self. As Hegel explained, the multiplication of desires is caused by the division of labour, because the division of labour produces a multitude of products that excite a multiplicity of desires. The members of the system of commodity pro- ducers need to produce wealth, a vast accumulation of commodities, if they are to expand value and to attain wealth themselves. Desires stimulated by producers of wealth are desires for par- ticles of wealth. The chocolate industry exposes prospective consumers to a multiplicity of chocolate products which excite interest in these products. It does so by displaying the product in widely distributed retail sites, and by extensive advertising in magazines, newspapers, televi- sion, radio, movies, and on the Internet. The industry assures its own growth by establishing ‘almost infinite points of sale’ where desires are excited.61 With an estimated ‘2 million places where confectionary can be purchased in the United States,’ the opportunities for exciting inter- 57 Rees (note 55 above) at 127. 58 The Chocolate Market (2001) at 31 Web publication by MarketResearch.com Academic: www.academ- ic.marketresearch.com/product/print/default.asp?. 59 The Chocolate Market (note 58 above) at 31. 60 Rees ‘Bite-Sized Marketing’ (note 55 above) at 128. 61 The Chocolate Market (note 58 above) at 68. est are truly vast.62 Sites for exposing consumers to chocolate products have expanded out from candy stores to supermarkets, gourmet and specialty stores, convenience stores, mass mer- chandisers, vending machines, drugstores, warehouse clubs, hardware stores, office supply stores, video stores, craft and hobby stores, health and natural foods stores, the internet,63 and car washes. The upscale Toblerone brand is now available at the best truck stops. Marketing through cross promotions and tie-ins also stimulates a lot of interest in chocolate. After ET reached for a Reece’s peanut butter cup, the brand’s sales tripled.64 The tie-in to Lindberg’s solo flight across the Atlantic launched the Lindy Bar.65 Advertising also excites interest in chocolate. National consumer advertising expenditures in 1999 reached an estimat- ed $369 million.66 Hershey spends 10 percent of its enormous yearly sales on advertising67 giv- ing it considerable capacity to stimulate desires for its chocolate. If Chris Armstrong really purchased chocolate just because he liked it, rather than because his desire for it is a desire for a part of social wealth, then his desire would have no common- ality with the desires of those who do not like chocolate. Consequently, we would be unable to establish that consumers have common goals. But as we have seen, the desire for chocolate is a quantitatively and qualitatively multiplied desire. As such, it has the shared property of being a desire for wealth. The common desire for wealth establishes a dimension of community among citizens, which invokes the ethics of community and its egalitarian rules of distribution of part of national income. (E) CAN THERE BE COMMUNITY IN MARKET ECONOMIES WITH DISSIDENT ENVIRONMENTALISTS AND SUSTAINABLE ECONOMISTS AROUND? The proposition that capital-based market systems have a dimension of community is apparently contradicted by the fact that these systems contain economic democrats, right- and left-wing liber- tarians, market socialists, devotees of sustainable economics, all advocating alternative economic arrangements: a system of self-owned and self-governing economic enterprises, unregulated capi- talism, a system of collectively owned and self-managed firms, a system with highest attainable basic income, etc. Some proponents of these systems view them as categorically different from, and ethically superior to, capital-based market systems with egalitarian rules of distribution derived from the ethics of community. 68 As they see it, the ethics of community for capital-based market systems does not provide principles of distributive justice that are generally valid for all economic systems or specifically valid for capital-based market systems. Some theorists doubt that commu- nity could be ascribed to systems fraught with this much dissensus.69 Disagreement between individuals in a capital-based market system regarding distributive rules may not rule out a dimension of community regarding some or all of the system’s funda- mentals. While economic actors may disagree over whether there should be liberal property or redistributory property, they may agree that the economy should be arranged so as to preserve Opening the Door to More Equality 285 62 The Chocolate Market (note 58 above) at 20. 63 The Chocolate Market (note 58 above) at 68. 64 Lopez Chocolate (note 54 above) at 126 65 Lopez Chocolate (note 54 above) at 126. 66 The Chocolate Market (note 58 above) at 18. 67 Rees ‘Bite-Sized Marketing’ (note 55 above) at 127. 68 V Chibber ‘Individualism, Community, and Distributive Justice’ (2004) 13 The Good Society 62 at 62-66. 69 Armstrong ‘Equality’ (note 37 above) at 346 fn 23. 2 8 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E and expand capital. As long as they agree on this relevant fundamental, a dimension of com- munity can exist within capital-based market systems, and it can invoke the redistributory rules of the ethics of community. Even if the minority prefers traditional liberal property rights, the majority can cite the agreement on the preservation and expansion of capital as a communal basis for the egalitarian rules of distribution of the ethics of community. Disagreement between individuals in capital-based market systems regarding private versus collective ownership of production precludes some forms of community among the members. But it does not rule out agreement on a relevant fundamental: that the system should be arranged so that capital is preserved and expanded, and wealth created and acquired. Community in regard to the preservation and maintenance of capital can, therefore, exist in a capital-based market systems, despite the lack of community with respect to whether there should be collective versus decentralized ownership of firms. And it can invoke the egalitarian distributive rules of the ethics of community. Do differences between advocates of capital-based systems and sustainable economies pre- clude an element of economic community from the former systems? And therefore also pre- clude the ethics of economic community with their egalitarian rules of distribution? I don’t think so. Sustainable economics rejects growth economics and adopts steady-state economics. Its advo- cates define growth as ‘an increase in the physical scale of the matter/energy throughput that sus- tains the economic activities of production and consumption commodities.’70 If adherents of sus- tainable economics were right that economic growth could be defined as an increase in the amount of physical inputs and physical outputs, then a sustainable economy that eliminates this kind of increase would obviously be categorically different from a capital-based economy, where increases in physical inputs and outputs are ongoing. But economic growth cannot be reduced to increased use of physical inputs (raw materials and capital stock) and increased production of physical outputs. New generations of computers, refrigerators, televisions, and other electronic devices can have innovative features that add to their value, even though their production does not utilize as much matter and energy as previous generations did. Since the growth of capital consists essentially in the growth of value, the limitation of physical inputs and outputs that sus- tainable economics requires does not necessarily limit capital’s growth. A sustainable develop- ment model is, at least in this fundamental respect, indistinguishable from a capital-based mar- ket system. Disagreements between the advocates of these alternatives systems do not bar the existence of community with respect to the preservation and expansion of value, so the commu- nal basis exists for the ethics of community and its egalitarian rule of distribution. As the natural resource constraint upon physical growth tightens, however, countries will have to try to shift from the mode of expansion of capital under capitalism to the mode of expansion of capital in the sustainable economy. Instead of expanding capital through expan- sion of physical inputs and outputs there will be an intensified drive to expand it through expanding value—without expansion of physical inputs and outputs. If, on the one hand, this works, then capital-based markets will be preserved. If, on the other hand, economic society cannot convert to the alternative mode of value expansion, then the economy will cease to be a value-growth system and will lose a basic feature of a capital-based market system (though it can still have another basic feature of a capital-based market, which I will mention in a moment). Community will not obtain between the advocates of sustainable and wealth-based 70 Herman Daly Beyond Growth (1996) at 31. economics with respect to continued expansion, and to this extent there will not be a basis on which to argue for the ethics of community with its egalitarian rules of distribution. There will, however, continue to be agreement with respect to the pursuit and acquisition of a portion of wealth, considered as a vast amount of wealth involving an immense accumulation of com- modities, though not as a growing sum and possibly as a retreating sum. This degree and kind of community would also continue to justify egalitarian distribution proportionate to the extent of community. The number of advocates of expansionary capital-based economics will probably dwindle under circumstances of severe resource constraints, just as support for capitalism waned after World War II in Europe, where a new consensus on the mixed economy arose. In this case, there would be community with respect to the mode of value creation in the sustainable economy, which would invoke egalitarian rules of community. Suppose that capital-based market systems can successfully change to economic growth involving expansion of value without expansion of physical inputs and outputs. Then it would seem like the ethics of capital-based economic community would still be valid. The common goals of the members — preservation and expansion of capital and the creation and acquisition of wealth — would not have hit an insuperable barrier. People would continue to have a com- mon interest in the preservation and expansion of capital, except that it would take the form of a common interest in the preservation and expansion of value rather than of physical inputs and outputs. The egalitarian rules of distribution would still be invoked, because community had been maintained. In sum, there is a communal element in both sustainable economics and capital-based mar- ket systems. Indeed the former can be capital-based market systems and can have the dimen- sion of community that the latter have. Under certain circumstances, however, they will cease to be species of capital-based systems. When resource constraints are very severe, sustainable economies will not be capital-based market systems, and they will lack at least some of the forms of community that reside in the latter systems. But they will have a different dimension of community, one that obtains with respect to the mode of value creation characteristic of a sustainable economy, and that dimension of community will invoke the rules of the ethics of community. The ethics of community, therefore, seem general in their application to the various types of modern real world economies. (F) ON THE MARXIST CRITIQUE OF THE ETHICS OF COMMUNITY FOR CAPITAL-BASED MARKETS In the judgment of some radical and liberal analysts, cooperative relations between owners and workers do not display an element of community, because these relations do not arise from free, uncoerced choices. Labour deals with capital on pain of starvation, not out of a community of interests. This line of critique seeks to undermine the communal thesis by refuting the premis- es on which it is based. But I do not think the attempt is successful. One of the premises of com- munity is that labour and capital share an interest in preserving and expanding wealth and cap- ital. Another is that labour has an interest in creating and consuming a share of social wealth. Neither one of these premises can be set aside by arguing that labour cooperates with capital on pain of starvation. To refute these premises, one would have to show labour could success- fully pursue its interest in a share of social wealth without proceeding in accordance with the requirements for preserving and expanding capital. As far as I know, neo-Marxist and liberal Opening the Door to More Equality 287 2 8 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E arguments have not shown this, so the communal dimension remains well founded. The argument that cooperation in capitalism is necessitous rather than volitional hinges on a neo-Marxist or classical political economic view of how capital provides for the needs of workers. On this view, capitalism affords the bare minimum for workers’ needs, if that. But the classical model does not square with the facts, noted above, of the twenty-first century Ameri- can economy. With thirty five million white collar workers receiving mean hourly earnings of 19 dollars, fifteen million workers in professional specialty and technical occupations with average earnings of 26.18 dollars, twenty three million blue collar workers with mean hourly earnings of 13.61 dollars, and fourteen million workers in state and local governments receiv- ing mean hourly earnings of 20.56 dollars, workers in twenty-first century America share enough in the ends of association for the economy to have a substantial dimension of commu- nity, though not equally enough for the distributive ethics of community to be fully realized.71 The presence of an element of community makes the ethics of community applicable to capi- talism to the extent that community exists within it. Because this ethics morally entails equal- ization, there should be an equalization of income proportionate to the extent of community present in the system. Once the redistributive rules of ethical community are applied, they can reduce the antago- nism in capital-labour relations. That antagonism is treatable by these external rules partly because the antagonism is not entirely intrinsic to these relations. And, to the extent that the antagonism is intrinsic, it can still be substantially overcome by external measures. The antag- onism between labour and capital arises in part from an external source: liberal laws of prop- erty and contract which promote income inequality by giving legal authorization to almost any terms that capital and labour agree upon. It is therefore susceptible to reduction by redistribu- tive measures which alter the external legal environment of business that currently authorizes highly unequal incomes. Marxists in particular believe that external redistributive policies cannot significantly en- hance community between labour and capital, because the antagonism springs from sources intrinsic to their relations rather than extrinsic to them. Under competitive market conditions, capitalistic owners who seek to maximize profits must minimize costs by, among other things, keeping wages down. For this reason, Marxists contend that wage conflict is built into capital- labour relations and that it is unalterable so long as private ownership of capital exists. Since the antagonism between workers and owners is a function of the private ownership and con- trol of firms, Marxists contend that it cannot be overcome by governmental policies in regard to welfare or redistribution. While the antagonism between labour and capital does, as Marxists claim, have some internal causes within capitalism, the fact that the sources of wage conflict are internal does not put the antagonism beyond the ameliorative reach of redistribu- tive policies. Redistributive measures can reach the inequality of incomes wherever it arises, inside or outside the economy. And, by allowing workers to share more fully in the ends of asso- ciation, these measures are able to strengthen the bonds of association. From the perspective of neo-Marxists and some liberals, wage conflict is inherent in capital- ism, so it can not be eradicated or significantly reduced under capitalism, because there is a zero-sum relation between profit and wages. It is true that profits and wages are partially inversely related, but they are not entirely inversely related. A partially inverse relation between wages and profits precludes a fully communal relationship between labour and capital, but it 71 See National Compensation Survey: Occupational Wages in the United States, 2001. does not preclude a partially communal one. A dimension of community is, therefore, compat- ible with a partially inverse relationship between wages and profits. Profits are important for capital accumulation, and capital accumulation is an essential input to long-term growth, which in turn is one of the most important causes of rising standards of living.72 As Joel Mokyr puts it, ‘To say … that a country is rich is to say that it experienced economic growth in the past.’73 Both workers and owners of capital can, therefore, have some common interest in profit max- imization and cost minimization. This means that the opposition between workers and owners of capital as regards wages and profits is not thoroughgoing and that it can co-exist with an element of community. When one adds this aspect of community to other aspects that the sys- tem possesses, there are gathering bases for invoking an ethics of community and applying its egalitarian rules to the distribution of income in capital-based market systems. Marxists also believe that antagonism is intrinsic because workers and owners hold different values and act from different motivational goals. And they think that these motivational dif- ferences give rise to conflicts that can only be eradicated or reduced by changing the basic form of ownership and control, not by promulgating redistributive measures. In a competitive envi- ronment, wealth-seeking capitalists organize the labour process so as ‘to extract the maximum quantum of effort from workers.’ 74 This inevitably pits capitalists against workers, who value ‘leisure over work’ and even ‘shirk[] from it where possible.’75 Though this might undermine the preservation of capital, workers do not care, because they are motivated by a ‘different set of incentives.’ ‘Given the different set of incentives motivating labour and capital,’ some Marxists argue that ‘the employment relation comes to involve an irreducible element of con- flict—not over distribution, but over autonomy and control.’76 To focus on simple inequality of incomes is ignore other more important conflicts that are irresolvable within the context of capitalism. In the Marxist view there is, therefore, no community to speak of. The fact that workers and owners differ about the appropriate pace and quantity of work does not mean, however, that they hold fundamentally different values. The view that workers value leisure over income is another feature of classical political economic and Marxist models, which posit that labour seeks subsistence rather than a share of wealth. The worker who val- ues leisure over work does not seem, however, to be the worker that inhabits advanced capi- talist economies. Workers integrated into the wealth-seeking ethos of the modern economy tend to value work over leisure or money-incomes over leisure. Shirking by workers does not mean that they seek subsistence rather than wealth. Executives for that matter are just as capable of shirking as workers are, yet no one adduces a desire for subsistence as an explanation for it. Shirking, whether by workers or owners, is instead symptomatic of an organizational patholo- gy, which leads them to believe that a share of wealth can be had without working. Since the modern worker shares the owner’s desire for a share of wealth, and she is not moti- vated by utterly different incentives, her values cannot be sharply distinguished from those of owners of capital. The differences between thee goals of workers and owners do not, therefore, constitute an intrinsic source of conflict over ownership and control that is so thoroughgoing that all elements of community are vitiated from labour capital relations. And, broadening our account of points of conflict from simple inequality of income to ownership and control of Opening the Door to More Equality 289 72 Philippe Aghion & Peter Howitt Endogenous Growth Theory (1999) at 114. 73 Joel Mokyr The Lever of Riches (1990) at 3. 74 Chibber ‘Individualism, Community, and Distributive Justice’ (2004) 13 The Good Society 62 at 64 . 75 Chibber (note 74 above) at 64. 76 Chibber (note 74 above) at 64. 2 9 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E firms has not, contrary to Marxist theory, revealed oppositions of interests so thoroughgoing that they preclude all significant elements of community. The differences that Marxist and classical theory posits between the values of workers and owners may also not hold with respect to workers in developing countries. In countries of this sort with highly unequal distributions of income, workers sometimes appear to have a prefer- ence for leisure over monetary reward, but this may not be their real preference. In these economies poor workers do not have much capital to work with, so they can only expect to receive low payoffs from hard work. If redistribution were implemented, ‘so that the payoffs are more equally shared,’ Aghion and Howitt contend, the incentives of the poor will be raised and this will raise output.77 In sum, the element of community is not refuted by any supposedly thoroughgoing conflict over autonomy and control arising from irreducible differences between the values of workers and owners. This element of community continues to invoke the ethics of community with respect to capital-based market systems, requiring egalitarian redistribution of a portion of national income. 77 Aghion & Howitt (note 72 above) at 318. Bibliography A Abel R A Time of Trouble: Law and Liberty in South Africa’s State of Emergency (1992) Abbott-Smith G A Manual Greek Lexicon of the New Testament (1977) Acemoglu D ‘Root Causes. A Historical Approach to Assessing the Role of Institutions in Economic Development’ (2003) 40 Finance and Development 27 Ackermann L ‘Equality and the South African Constitution: The Role of Dignity’ (2000) 60 The Heidelberg Journal for International Law 537 Aghion P & P Howitt Endogenous Growth Theory (1999) Albertyn C ‘Equality’ in M H Cheadle, D M Davis and N R L Haysom (eds) South African Constitutional Law: The Bill of Rights (1990) Albertyn C & B Goldblatt ‘Facing the Challenge of Transformation: Difficulties in the Development of an Indigenous Jurisprudence of Equality’ (1998) 14 SAJHR 248 Altizer TJJ The Genesis of God – A Theological Genealogy (1993) Archer M ‘The Private Life of The Social Agent: What Difference Does It Make?’ in J Cruickshank (ed) Critical Realism. The Difference it Makes (2003) 91 Armstrong C ‘Equality, Community, and the Production of Value’ 2004 European Journal of Political Theory 339 Aron J ‘Growth and Institutions: A Review of Evidence’ (2000) 15(1) The World Bank Observer 99 Ashcraft R ‘Liberalism and the Problem of Poverty’ (1992) 6 Crit Rev 493 Assmann J et al Gerechtigkeit: Richten und Retten in der abendländischen Tradition und ihren altorien- talischen Ursprüngen (1998) August KT The Quest for Being Public Church (2003) DTh thesis, University of Stellenbosch, Stellen- bosch B Bachmann M ‘Would Social Health Insurance Improve South African Health Care? What other Middle Income Countries Can Teach Us’ (1994) 24 Transformation 26 Balderman I et al (eds) Menschenwürde: JBTh 15 (2001) Balz H ‘Die Gerechtigkeit der Gerechtfertigten: eine neutestamentliche Skizze’ in P Dabrock et al (eds) Kriterien der Gerechtigkeit (2003) 45 Barberton C ‘Progressive Realisation’ of Socio-Economic Rights’ (1999) 2 Economic and Social Rights Review 1 Barenberg M ‘Democracy and Domination in the Law of Workplace Cooperation: From Bureaucratic to Flexible Production’ (1994) 94 Col LR 753 Baron M, P Pettit & M Slote Three Methods of Ethics: A Debate (1999) Barth K Church Dogmatics (1960) Barth K Texte zur Barmer Theologischen Erklärung (1984) Barth K The Humanity of God (1967) Baumol WJ ‘Entrepreneurship: Productive, Unproductive and Destructive’ (1990) 89 Journal of Political Economy 893 Baur J (ed) Zum Thema Menschenrechte: theologische Versuche und Entwürfe (1977) 2 9 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E Bebchuk L, J Fried & D Walker ‘Managerial Power and Rent Extraction in the Design of Executive Compensation’ (2002) 69 University of Chicago LR 751 Bedford-Strohm H Vorrang für die Armen: auf dem Weg zu einer theologischen Theorie der Gerechtigkeit (1993) Bell W Aid to Dependent Children (1965) Bellah R et al Habits of the Heart. Individualism and Commitment in American Life (1985) Bellah R et al The Good Society (1991) Ben-Bassat A & M Dahan ‘Social Rights in the Constitution and in Practice’ Hebrew U of Jerusalem School of Public Policy Working Paper No 05-03 May 2003 Benedict ML ‘Laissez-Faire and Liberty: A Reevaluation of the Meaning and Origins of Laissez-Faire Constitutionalism’ (1985) 3 Law & History Review 293 Bennett T & C Powell ‘Aboriginal Title in South Africa Revisited’ (1999) 15 SAJHR 449 Bennis P ‘Talking Points: Iraq, the UN, & US Corporations’ (2003) Web publication by United for Peace and Justice http://unitedforpeace.org/article.php?id=2031 Berlin I ‘Two Concepts of Liberty’ in I Berlin (ed) Fours Essays on Liberty (1969) 118 Berger P (ed) The Desecularization of the World. Resurgent Religion and World Politics (1999) Best TF and M Robra (eds) Ecclesiology and Ethics: Ecumenical Engagement, Moral Formation and the Nature of the Church (1997) Best TF and M Robra ‘Introduction’ in TF Best and M Robra (eds) Ecclesiology and Ethics: Ecumenical Engagement, Moral Formation and The Nature of the Church (1997) vii Bhaskar R ‘On the Possibility of Social Scientific Knowledge and the Limits of Naturalism’ in J Mepham & DH Rubin (eds) Issues in Marxist Philosophy vol 3: Epistemology, Science, Ideology (1979) 125 Biko S I Write What I Like (2004) Bilchitz D ‘Giving Socio-Economic Rights Teeth: The Minimum Core and its Importance’ (2002) 118 SALJ 484 Birch B & L Rasmussen Bible and Ethics in the Christian Life (1989) Bix B Jurisprudence: Theory and Context (1996) Bloch FS ‘Cooperative Federalism and the Role of Litigation in the Development of Federal AFDC Eligibility Policy’ (1979) Wis LR 1 Botha H ‘Freedom and Constraint in Constitutional Adjudication’ (2004) 20 SAJHR 249 Botha H, A van der Walt & J van der Walt (eds) Rights and Democracy in a Transformative Constitution (2004) Botha J & P Naude Op Pad met Belhar: Goeie Nuus vir Gister, Vandag en Môre (1998) Botman HR ‘Human Dignity and Economic Globalization’ in HR Botman & K Sporre (eds) Building a Human Rights Culture: South African and Swedish Perspectives (2003) 20 Bosniak LS ‘Critical Reflection on “Citizenship” as a Progressive Aspiration’ in J Conaghan, RM Fischl & K Klare (eds) Labour Law in an Era of Globalization: Transformative Practices and Possibilities (2002) 339 Brady BV The Moral Bond of Community: Justice and Discourse in Christian Morality (1998) Brand D & S Russell Exploring the Core Content of Socio-Economic Rights: South African and International Perspectives (2002) Brand D ‘Introduction to Socio-Economic Rights in the South African Constitution’ in D Brand & CH Heyns (eds) Socio-Economic Rights in South Africa (2005) 1 Brand D ‘The Proceduralisation of South African Socio-Economic Rights Jurisprudence, or “What are Socio-Economic Rights For?”’ in H Botha, A van der Walt & J van der Walt (eds) Rights and Democracy in a Transformative Constitution (2004) 33 Breitenberg EH ‘To Tell the Truth: Will the Real Public Theology Please Stand Up?’ (2003) 23 Journal of the Society of Christian Ethics 55 Brodsky G ‘Gosselin v Quebec (Attorney General): Autonomy with a Vengeance’ (2003) 15 Canadian Journal of Women and the Law 194 Brown S & A Fölscher Taking Power in the Economy – Gains and Directions (2004) Browning D A Fundamental Practical Theology. Descriptive and Strategic Proposals (1996) Brunner E Dogmatics (1950) Brunner E Gerechtigkeit: eine Lehre von den Grundgesetzen der Gesellschaftsordnung (1943) Buchanan A ‘The Right to a Decent Minimum of Health Care’ (1984) 13(1) Philosophy and Public Affairs 55 Buchanan JM & RA Musgrave Public Finance and Public Choice. Two Contrasting Visions of the State (2000) Buchanan JM ‘Politics without Romance’ in JM Buchanan (ed) The Collected Works of James Buchanan. Volume I. The Logical Foundations of Constitutional Liberty (1999) 45 Buchanan R ‘Border Crossings: NAFTA, Regulatory Restructuring, and the Politics of Place’ (1995) 2 Indiana J of Global Legal Studies 371 Budlender D The People’s Voices (1998) Burgsmüller A & R Weth (eds) Die Barmer Theologische Erklärung: Einführung und Dokumentation (1983) Burke E ‘Reflections on the Revolution in France’ in E Burke (ed) On Taste; On the Sublime and Beautiful; Reflections on the French Revolution; A Letter to a Noble Lord (1937) 143 Busch E Die Barmer Thesen 1934 - 2004 (2004) C Calitz E & K Siebritz: ‘Macroeconomic Stability and Developmental Expectations: Fiscal Consolidation in Post-Apartheid South Africa’ (2003) Cameron E ‘Legal Chauvinism, Executive-Mindedness and Justice: L C Steyn’s Impact on South African Law’ (1982) 99 SALJ 38 Casper G ‘Changing Concepts of Constitutionalism: 18th to 20th Century’ (1989) S Ct Rev 311 Chanock M The Making of South African Legal Culture 1902-1936: Fear, Favour and Prejudice (2001) Chapman A ‘Core Obligations Related to the Right to Health and their Relevance for South Africa’ (2002) in D Brand & S Russell Exploring the Core Content of Socio-Economic Rights: South African and International Perspectives (2002) 35 Chetty K ‘The Public Finance Implications of Recent Socio-Economic Rights Judgments’ (2002) 6 Law, Democracy and Development 231 Chibber V ‘Individualism, Community, and Distributive Justice’ (2004) 13 The Good Society 62 Clark HB Serenity, Courage, and Wisdom: The Enduring Legacy of Reinhold Niebuhr (1994) Clements K Learning to Speak: The Church’s Voice in Public Affairs (1995) Cloete GD & DJ Smit A Moment of Truth: The Confession of the Dutch Reformed Mission Church (1984) Cloete JJN Administration of Health Services (1981) Coase RH ‘The Institutional Structure of Production’ in RH Coase (ed) Essays on Economics and Economists (1994) 3 Cockrell A ‘Rainbow Jurisprudence’ (1996) 12 SAJHR 1 Cohen WJ ‘The Social Security Act of 1935: Reflections Fifty Years Later’ in The Report of the Committee on Economic Security of 1935 at 3 (50th Anniversary ed Natl Conf on Soc Welfare 1985) Collier P & JW Gunning ‘Explaining African Economic Performance’ (1999) 37 Journal of Economic Literature 64 Bibliography 293 2 9 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E Commons JR Legal Foundations of Capitalism (1924) Conaghan J ‘Woman, Work and Family: A British Revolution’ in J Conaghan, RM Fischl & K Klare (eds) Labour Law in an Era of Globalization: Transformative Practices and Possibilities (2002) 53 Conaghan J, RM Fischl & K Klare (eds) Labour Law in an Era of Globalization: Transformative Practices and Possibilities (2002) Coons JE et al ‘Educational Opportunity: A Workable Constitutional Test for State Financial Structures’ (1969) 57 Cal LR 305 Corder H Judges at Work: The Role and Attitudes of the South African Appellate Judiciary, 1910-50 (1984) Courage N ‘WTO Agreement Improves Access to Life-Saving Drugs’ The Lawyers Weekly 2003-09-26 Cover R Justice Accused: Antislavery and the Judicial Process (1975) Cowen S ‘Can “Dignity” Guide South Africa’s Equality Jurisprudence?’ (2001) 17 SAJHR 34 Cranston M ‘Human Rights, Real and Supposed’ in DD Raphael (ed) Political Theory and the Rights of Man (1967) 51 Crüsemann F ‘Jahwes Gerechtigkeit im Alten Testament’ (1976) 36 Evangelische Theologie 427 Cupitt D The Long-legged Fly (1987) Currie DP ‘Positive and Negative Constitutional Rights’ (1986) 53 Univ of Chicago LR 864 Currie DP The Constitution of the Federal Republic of Germany (1994) D Dabrock P et al (eds) Kriterien der Gerechtigkeit: Festschrift für Christofer Frey zum 65. Geburtstag (2003) Daly H Beyond Growth (1996) Daniels N ‘Health Care Needs and Distributive Justice’ (1981) 10 Philosophy and Public Affairs 146 Daniels N ‘A Reply to Stern Critics and a Remark on Health Care Rights’ (1983) 8 Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 363 Davis DM ‘The Case Against the Inclusion Of Socio-Economic Demands In a Bill of Rights Except as Directive Principles’ (1992) 8 SAJHR 475 Davis DM ‘Equality: The Majesty of Legoland Jurisprudence’ (1999) 116 SALJ 398 Davis DM Democracy and Deliberation (1999) Davis DM ’Elegy to Transformative Constitutionalism’ in H Botha, AJ van der Walt & J van der Walt (eds) Rights and Democracy in a Transformative Constitution (2004) 57 Davis DM ‘Socio-Economic Rights in South Africa. The Record of the Constitutional Court after Ten Years’ (2004) 5:5 ESR Review 3 Davis MF Brutal Need: Lawyers and The Welfare Rights Movement, 1960-1973 (1993) De Beer C ‘A Forward View of the Health Services in South Africa’ (1976) 50 South African Medical Journal 431 De Beer C ‘Explaining the Present: Why Health Services do not meet the Health Needs of the Population’ in A Zwi & WB Saunders (ed) Towards Health Care for All (1985) 59 Debreu G Theory of Value: An Axiomatic Analysis of Economic Equilibrium (1959) De Buen Unna C ‘Mexican Trade Unionism in a Time of Transition’ in J Conaghan, RM Fischl & K Klare (eds) Labour Law in an Era of Globalization: Transformative Practices and Possibilities (2002) 401 De Gruchy SM Not Liberation but Justice: An Analysis of Reinhold Niebuhr’s Understanding of Human Destiny in the Light of the Doctrine of the Atonement (1992) DTh thesis, University of the Western Cape, Bellville De Gruchy J Christianity and Democracy. A Theology for a Just World Order (1995) De Gruchy J ‘African Theology: South Africa’ in D Ford (ed) The Modern Theologians. An Introduction to Christian Theology in the Twentieth Century (1997) 445 De Long JB & A Shleifer ‘Princes and Merchants: European City Growth before the Industrial Revolution’ (1993) 36 Journal of Law and Economics 671 Derthick M The Influence of Federal Grants: Public Assistance in Massachusetts (1970) De Vos P ‘Grootboom, The Right of Access to Housing and Substantive Equality as Contextual Fairness’ (2001) 17 SAJHR 258 De Waal J, I Currie & MG Erasmus The Bill of Rights Handbook (4th ed) (2001) Diamond J Guns, Germs and Steel. The Fates of Human Societies (1997) Dicey AV Lectures on Law and Public Opinion in England During the Nineteenth Century (1905) Dietsch P ‘Review of Ross Zucker Democratic Distributive Justice’ (2002) 14 The Review of Political Economy 397 Dollar D & A Kraay ‘Growth is Good for the Poor’ (2001) World Bank Policy Research Working Paper Series 2587 Donnely J Universal Human Rights in Theory and Practice (1989) Dorrington RE et al The Impact of HIV/AIDS on Adult Mortality in South Africa (2001) Duchrow U ‘Justice’ in N Lossky et al (eds) Dictionary of the Ecumenical Movement (2002) 627 Dugard J ‘The Judicial Process, Positivism and Civil Liberty’ (1971) 88 SALJ 181 Dugard J Human Rights and the South African Legal Order (1978) Dugard J ‘Should Judges Resign? A Reply to Professor Wacks’ (1984) 101 SALJ 286 Durkheim E Suicide. A study in Sociology (1952) Durkheim E Professional Ethics and Civic Morals (1957) Durkheim E The Rules of Sociological Method and Selected Texts on Sociology and its Method (1982) Durkheim E The Division of Labour in Society (1984) Durkheim E The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (1995) Du Toit D (ed) Menseregte: Opstelle (1984) Du Toit D Die Mens en sy Regte: Geloof en Praktyk in Suid-Afrika (1988) Du Toit SF Ideas of Truth and Revelation in the Light of the Challenge of Postmodernism (1995) University of Oxford: DPhil Thesis Du Toit SF Learning to Live Together: Practices of Social Reconciliation (2003) Dworkin R Taking Rights Seriously (1977) Dworkin R ‘What Is Equality: Part 2: Equality of Resources’ (1981)10 Philosophy and Public Affairs 283 Dworkin R ‘Why We Are All Liberals’ paper presented at the Program for the Study of Law, Philosophy & Social Theory NYU School of Law 19 October 1995 Dykstra C& DC Bass ‘A Theological Understanding of Christian Practices’ in M Volf & DC Bass Practicing Theology. Beliefs and Practices in Christian Life (2002) 13 Dyzenhaus D Hard Cases in Wicked Legal Systems: South African Law in the Perspective of Legal Philosophy (1991) Dyzenhaus D Truth, Reconciliation and the Apartheid Legal Order (1998) E Easterly W The Elusive Quest for Growth (2001) Edelman MW Lanterns: A Memoir of Mentors (1999) Eggertsson T Economic Behaviour and Institutions (1990) Elkin SL ‘Notes on the Old Political Science for the Present Age’ (2004) 1 The Good Society 4 Ellmann S In a Time of Trouble: Law and Liberty in South Africa’s State of Emergency (1992) Engelhardt HT ‘Rights to Health Care: A Critical Appraisal’ (1979) 4 Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 113 Etzioni A The Moral Dimension (1988) Bibliography 295 2 9 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E F Fabre C Social Rights under the Constitution: Government and the Decent Life (2000) Falconer AD ‘Pressing the Claims: Reflections in the Theological Basis of Human Rights’ (1998) 48 Reformed World 50 Feldman D Civil Liberties and Human Rights in England and Wales (1993) Feuerbach L The Essence of Christianity (1989, 1st ed 1841) Fineman MLA ‘Masking Dependency: The Political Role of Family Rhetoric’ (1995) 81 Virginia LR 2181 Fischer J ‘Jenseits reiner Normativität: Skizze einer theologisch-ethischen Annäherung and die Gerechtig- keitsthematik’ in P Dabrock et al (eds) Kriterien der Gerechtigkeit (2003) 137 Forbath WE ‘The Ambiguities of Free Labor: Labor and the Law in the Gilded Age’ (1985) Wis LR 767 Forbath WE ‘Habermas’s Constitution: A History, Guide, and Critique’ (1998) 23 L & Soc Inquiry 969 Forbath WE ‘Caste, Class, and Equal Citizenship’ (1999) 98 Mich LR 1 Forbath WE ‘“Constitutional Welfare Rights”: A History, Critique and Reconstruction’ (2001) 69 Fordham LR 1821 Forbath WE ‘The New Deal Constitution in Exile’ (2001) 51 Duke LJ 165 Forbath WE ‘Lincoln, the Declaration, and the “Grisly, Undying Corpse of States’ Rights”: History, Memory, and Imagination in the Constitution of a Southern Liberal’ (2004) 92 Georgetown LJ 709 Forbath WE ‘Not So Simple Justice: Frank Michelman on Social Rights 1969-Present’ (2004) 39 Tulsa LR 597 Forrester D Christian Justice and Public Policy (1997) Forsyth C In Danger for their Talents: A Study of the Appellate Division of the Supreme Court of South Africa from 1950-80 (1985) Fouts DE ‘Policy-Making in the Supreme Court of Canada, 1950-1960’ in G Schubert & DJ Danelski (eds) Comparative Judicial Behavior: Cross-Cultural Studies of Political Decision-Making in the East and West (1969) 257 Frank J Law and the Modern Mind (1930) Fraser N ‘Talking about Needs: Interpretive Contests as Political Conflicts in Welfare-State Societies’ (1989) 99 Ethics 291 Fraser N & L Gordon ‘A Genealogy of Dependency: Tracing a Keyword of the US Welfare State’ (1994) 19 Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society 309 Fredman S ‘Providing Equality: Substantive Equality and the Positive Duty to Provide’ unpublished paper delivered at SAJHR Conference, 5 – 7 July 2004 G Garner BA (ed) Black’s Law Dictionary 7ed (1999) Gauri V ‘Social Rights and Economics. Claims to Health Care and Education in Developing Countries’ (2003) World Bank Policy Research Paper 3006 Gearon L Human Rights & Religion: A Reader (2002) Gelderblom D Morality, Individual and Society: Emile Durkheim (2004) Gewirth A ‘Are there any Absolute Rights?’ in J Waldron Theories of Rights (1984) 92 Giddens A Studies in Social and Political Theory (1977) Gilkey LB On Niebuhr: A Theological Study (2001) Glendon M ‘Rights in Twentieth-Century Constitutions’ (1992) 59 U Chi LR 519 Glendon M A World Made New: Eleanor Roosevelt and the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (2001) Gloppen R ‘Analyzing the Role of Courts in Social Transformation: Social Rights Litigation, Court Responsiveness and Capability’ paper presented at the Centre for Applied Legal Studies Workshop on Human Rights, Democracy and Social Transformation: When do Rights Work? (November 2003) Gloppen R, Rargarella & E Skaar (eds) Democratization and the Judiciary: The Accountability Function of Courts in New Democracies (2004) Goldberg AJ ‘Equality and Governmental Action’ (1964) 39 FNY U LR 205 Goldsmith AH et al ‘The Psychological Impact of Unemployment and Joblessness’ (1996) 25 J Socio-Eco 333 Goodin E, B Headey, R Muffels & HJ Dirven The Real Worlds of Welfare Capitalism (1999) Goyer KC ‘HIV/AIDS in South African Prisons’ http://www.iss.co.za/Pubs/Monographs/ No79/Chap1.html Graham C & S Pettinato Happiness and Hardship: Opportunity and Insecurity in New Market Economies (2002) Gray JC Restraints on the Alienation of Property (1895) Green W and J Neusner (eds) The Religion Factor. An Introduction to how Religion Matters (1996) Griffen D Primordial Truth and Postmodern Theology (1989) Grilli V, D Masciandaro et al ‘Institutions and Policies’ (1991) Economic Policy 341 Gustafson J ‘An Analysis of Church and Society Social Ethical Writings’ (1988) 40 Ecumenical Review 267 Gustafson J Varieties of Moral Discourse: Prophetic, Narrative, Ethical and Policy. The Stob Lectures of Calvin College and Seminary (1988) Gustafson J ‘Moral Discourse About Medicine: A Variety of Forms’ (1990) Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 125 H Habermas J ‘Law as Medium and Law as Institution’ in G Teubner (ed) Dilemmas of Law in the Welfare State (1986) 204 Habermas J The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity: Twelve Lectures (1987) Habermas J The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere: An Inquiry into a Category of Bourgeois Society (1989) Habermas J Erläuterungen zur Diskursethik (1991) Habermas J Faktizität und Geltung: Beiträge zur Diskurstheorie des Rechts und des demokratischen Rechtsstaats (1992) Habermas J Between Facts and Norms (1996) Habib A & C Skinner ‘The Poor Must Fend for Themselves’ (04-08-2002) Sunday Times 14 Hall KL The Magic Mirror (1989) Hall R ‘Rural Land Restitution in South Africa’ paper prepared for Programme for Land and Agrarian Studies (July 2003) Hall R & CI Jones ‘Why do Some Countries Produce so Much More Output per Worker than Others’ (1999) 114 Quarterly Journal of Economics 83 Handler JF & Y Hasenfeld We the Poor People: Work, Poverty, and Welfare (1997) Hardmeier C et al (eds) Freiheit und Recht: Festschrift für Frank Crüsemann zum 65. Geburtstag (2003) Hart HLA The Concept of Law (1961) Haspel M Protestantische Ethik vor der Herausforderung der Globalisierung (2004) Hauerwas S Vision and Virtue: Essays in Christian Ethical Reflection (1974) Hauerwas S Truthfulness and Tragedy: Further Investigations in Christian Ethics (1977) Hauerwas S A Community of Character: Toward a Constructive Christian Social Ethic (1981) Hauerwas S The Peaceable Kingdom. A Primer in Christian Ethics (1983) Hauerwas S Christian Existence Today. Essays on Church, World and Living in Between (1995) Bibliography 297 2 9 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E Hauerwas S & C Pinches Christians among the Virtues. Theological Conversations with Ancient and Modern Ethics (1997) Hauerwas S & S Wells (eds) The Blackwell Companion to Christian Ethics (2004) Hayek FA The Constitution of Liberty (1960) Hayek FA ‘Individualism: True and False’ in FA Hayek (ed) Individualism and Economic Order (1984) 1 Hayek FA ‘The Meaning of Competition’ in FA Hayek (ed) Individualism and Economic Order (1984) 92 Haysom N ‘Constitutionalism, Majoritarian Democracy and Socio-Economic Rights’ (1992) 2 SAJHR 451 Hegarty A & S Leonard Human Rights. An Agenda for the 21st Century (1999) Hegel GWF The Philosophy of Right (1952) Heller PS ‘Wealth Creation and Social Justice: An IMF perspective’ (2003) Paper Presented at the World Council of Churches/World Bank/IMF Meeting, February 2003 Hendriks H The Future of the Church, the Church of the Future (2004) Unpublished Inaugural lecture, University of Stellenbosch Heywood A Politics (2002) Heywood M ‘Preventing Mother-to-Child HIV Transmission in South Africa: Background, Strategies and Outcomes of the Treatment Action Campaign Case Against the Minister of Health’ (2003) 19 SAJHR 278 Hicks JR The Theory of Wages (1963) Hoctor S ‘Dignity, Criminal Law and the Bill of Rights’ (2004) 121 SALJ 265 Hofstadter R Social Darwinism in American Thought (1955) Honecker M Das Recht des Menschen: Einführung in die evangelische Sozialethik (1978) Hont I & M Ignatieff, Needs and Justice in the Wealth of Nations: An Introductory Essay, in Wealth and Virtue: The Shaping of Political Economy in the Scottish Enlightenment (1983) Horne TA Property Rights and Poverty: Political Argument in Britain, 1605-1834 (1990) Huber W & HE Tödt Menschenrechte: Perspektiven einer menschlichen Welt (1977) Huber W ‘Human Rights: A Concept and its History’ (1979) 124 Concilium 1 Huber W ‘Beten und Tun des Gerechten’ in W Huber & I Tödt (eds) Ethik im Ernstfall: Dietrich Bon- hoeffers Stellung zu den Juden und ihre Aktualitat (1982) 11 Huber W ‘Menschenrechte’ in Staatslexikon Bd. 3 (1987) Huber W ‘Recht im Horizont der Liebe’ in Brandt et al (eds) Ein Richter, ein Bürger, ein Christ: Festschrift für Helmut Simon (1987) 1045 Huber W ‘Justice, Peace and the Integrity of Creation: A Challenge for Ecumenical Theology’ (1988) 24 Scriptura 1 Huber W ‘Menschenrechte’ in L Engel et al (eds) Hoffnung in der Krise: Dokumente einer christlichen Existenz in Südafrika zum 65 Geburtstag von Wolfram Kistner (1988) 298 Huber W ‘Die Prediking oor Regverdigheid en Geregtigheid’ in CW Burger et al (eds) Riglyne vir Prediking oor die Bergrede (1990) 15 Huber W ‘Das Grundgesetz und die Menschenrechte’ (1989) 33 Zeitschrift für Evangelische Ethik 82 Huber W ‘Die Menschenrechte und das Grundgesetz: Theologische Überlegungen’ in M Pfeiffer (ed) Auftrag Grundgesetz: Wirklichkeit und Perspektiven (1989) 190 Huber W ‘Menschenrechte – Christenrechte’ in Recht nach Gottes Wort: Menschenrechte und Grund- rechte in Gesellschaft und Kirche (1989) 82 Huber W ‘Die Würde des Menschen ist antastbar: Anfragen aus der Sicht der christlichen Ethik’ (1990) 45 Universitas 852 Huber W Konflikt und Konsens: Studien zur Ethik der Verantwortung (1990) Huber W ‘Menschenrechte/Menschenwürde’ in Theologische Realencyklopädie XXII (1992) 577 Huber W ‘Menschenrechte und biblisches Rechtsdenken: ein Versuch’ (1993) 2 Neukirchener Theologische Zeitschrift: Kirche und Israel 144 Huber W Die tägliche Gewalt: gegen die Ausverkauf der Menschenwürde (1993) Huber W ‘Meschenwürde? Gewalt und Intimität als Unterhaltung’ in W Wunden (ed) Öffentlichkeit und Kommunikationskultur (1994) 181 Huber W ‘Gottesrecht und Menschenrechte in gesellschaftspolitischen Entwürfen’ (1995) 32 epd- Dokumentation 55 Huber W ‘Lebenswert und Lebensrecht’ (1995) Huber W ‘Die Würde des Menschen ist antastbar: Anfragen aus der Sicht der christlichen Ethik’ in S Abarbanell et al (eds) Fernsehzeit (1996) 185 Huber W Gerechtigkeit und Recht: Grundlinien Christlicher Rechtsethik (1996) Huber W ‘Recht als Beruf: Verantwortung für das Recht im Horizont der Gerechtigkeit’ in U Neumann and L Schulz (eds) Verantwortung in Recht und Moral: Referate der Tagung der Deutschen Sektion der Internationalen Vereinigung für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie (2000) 39 Huber W Rechtfertigung und Recht: über die christlichen Wurzeln der europäischen Rechtskultur (2001) Hunsinger G How to Read Karl Barth – The Shape of His Theology (1991) Huntington S The Clash of Civilizations and the Remaking of Worldorder (1997) Hütter R Evangelische Ethik als kirchliches Zeugnis: Interpretationen zu Schlüsselfragen theologischer Ethik in der Gegenwart (1993) I Iles K ‘Limiting Socio-Economic Rights: Beyond the Internal Limitations Clauses’ (2004) 20 SAJHR 448 J Jackman M ‘Constitutional Rhetoric and Social Justice: Reflections on the Justiciability Debate’ in J Bakan & D Schneiderman (eds) Social Justice and the Constitution: Perspectives on a Social Union for Canada (1992) 17 Jeeves A ‘Public Health and Epidemiology in the Era of South Africa’s VD Pandemic of the 1930s and 1940s’ paper read at AIDS in Context International Conference held at the University of the Witwatersrand 4–7 April 2001 Johanson B (ed) Human Rights in South Africa (1974) Johanson B Human Rights and Repression in Southern Africa: The Apartheid Machine Grinds On (1989) John C ‘Human Rights and the Churches: The New Challenges’ (1998) 48 Reformed World 79 Johnsen DE ‘Ronald Reagan and the Rehnquist Court on Congressional Power: Presidential Influences on Constitutional Change’ (2003) 78 Ind LJ 363 Jones J Labor of Love, Labor of Sorrow: Black Women, Work, and the Family from Slavery to the Present (1985) K Kagan D, S Ozment & FM Turner The Western Heritage to 1715 (2001) Kant I ‘On the Common Saying: “This May be True in Theory, But it Does not Apply in Practice’’’ in Hans Riess (ed) Kant’s Political Writings (1970) 61 Kant I The Moral Law: Kant’s Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals (1963) Kapp C ‘World Trade Organisation Reaches Agreement on Generic Medicines’ (2003) 362 Lancet 807 Kasper W & M E Streit Institutional Economics: Social Order and Public Policy (1998) Keeton C ‘A Turning Point for AIDS Treatment’ Sunday Times 2003-08-10 Kegley CW Reinhold Niebuhr, his Religious, Social, and Political Thought (1984) Bibliography 299 3 0 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E Kennedy D A Critique of Adjudication (Fin de Siècle) (1997) Keynes JM The General Theory of Employment, Interest, and Money (1964) Kindra J ‘AIDS: Ministers Revolt’ Mail & Guardian 2003-08-15 to 2003-08-21 Klaaren J ‘An Institutional Interpretation of Socio-Economic Rights and Judicial Remedies after TAC’ in H Botha, AJ van der Walt & J van der Walt (eds) Rights and Democracy in a Transformative Constitution (2004) 105 Klare KE ‘Judicial Deradicalization of the Wagner Act and the Origins of Modern Legal Consciousness’ (1978) 62 Minnesota LR 1049 Klare KE ‘Workplace Democracy and Market Reconstruction: An Agenda for Legal Reform’(1988) 38 Catholic University L Rev 1 Klare KE ‘Legal Culture and Transformative Constitutionalism’ (1998) 14 SAJHR 146 Knack S ‘Predation of Production? The Impact of Political, Legal and Social Institutions’ in S Knack (ed) Democracy, Governance and Growth (2003) 1 Knack S & P Keefer ‘Institutions and Economic Performance: Cross Country Tests Using Alternative Institutional Measures’ (1995) 7 Economics and Politics 207 Koopman N ‘Tussen die Duiwel van Konstantinisme en die Diep Blou See van Sektarisme – Kerk en Staat Verhoudinge in Post-apartheid Suid-Afrika’ (2001) 43 NGTT 135 Koopman N ‘ “... and the wronged…” A Basic and Neglected Conviction of (Reformed) Theology?’ in P Coertzen (ed) 350 Years Reformed 1652-2002 (2002) 252 Koopman N ‘Freedom of Religion and the Prophetic Role of the Church’ (2002) 43 NGTT 237 Koopman N ‘Some Comments About Public Theology Today’ (2003) Journal of Theology for Southern Africa 1 Koopman N ‘Defence in a Democracy. A Church Perspective on the Postapartheid Defence Review Process’ in K Haglind (ed) Arms Trade. Final Report from the 2nd Ecumenical Conference in Gothenburg (2004) 7 Koopman N ‘The Role of Tradition in Moral Decisionmaking and Moral Consensus’ (2004) 45 NGTT 838 Koopman N ‘Let the Plight of the Poor be Heard. Prophetic Speaking about Poverty Today’ (2004) 45 NGTT 440 Koopman N & R Vosloo Die Ligtheid van die Lig. Morele Oriëntasie in ‘n Postmoderne Tyd (2002) Küng H (ed) Yes to a global ethic (1996) Küng H & KJ Kuschel (eds) A Global Ethic. The Declaration of the Parliament of World Religions (1993) Kymlicka W Liberalism, Community and Culture (1989) L Ladd-Taylor M Mother-Work: Women, Child Welfare, and the State, 1890-1930 (1994) Landes D The Wealth and Poverty of Nations. Why Some are so Rich and Some so Poor (1998) Landes D The Unbound Prometheus: Technological Change and Industrial Development in Western Europe from 1750 to the Present (2003) Landman W ‘Appropriate Health Care as a Human Right’ in A Van Niekerk (ed) Health Care as Human Right (1993) 36 Lategan BC ‘Taking the Third Public Seriously’ in JW de Gruchy & S Martin (eds) Religion and the Reconstruction of Civil Society (1995) 217 Lawrence SE The Poor in Court: The Legal Services Program and Supreme Court Decision Making (1990) Lebacqz K Six Theories of Justice: Perspectives from Philosophical and Theological Ethics (1986) Lebacqz K Justice in an Unjust World: Foundations for a Christian Approach to Justice (1987) Leech BE ‘The Right of the HIV-positive Patient to Medical Care: An Analysis of Costs of Providing Medical Treatment’ (1993) 9 SAJHR 39 Levine DP Economic Theory (1978) Levine DP ‘Poverty, Capabilities, and Freedom’ (2003) 15 Review of Political Economy 101 Liebenberg S ‘The Right to Social Assistance: The Implications of Grootboom for Policy Reform in South Africa’ (2001) 17 SAJHR 232 Liebenberg S ‘South Africa’s Evolving Jurisprudence on Socio-Economic Rights: An Effective Tool in Challenging Poverty?’ (2002) 6 Law, Democracy and Development 159 Liebenberg S ‘The Interpretation of Socio-Economic Rights’ in M Chaskalson et al Constitutional Law of South Africa (2nd edition 2004) chap 33 Lienemann W Gerechtigkeit (1995) Lindblom CE Politics and Markets (1977) Lister R ‘Citizenship: Towards a Feminist Synthesis’ (1997) 57 Feminist Rev 28 Locke J Two Treatises of Government 170 (1960) Lopez R Chocolate: The Nature of Indulgence (2002) Lovin R Christian Ethics. An Essential Guide (2000) Lucas RJ ‘Econometric Policy Evaluation: A Critique’ in K Brunner & Meltzer AH (ed) The Phillips Curve and Labour Markets (1976) 19 Lucas RJ ‘Some Macroeconomics for the 21st Century’ (2000) 14 Journal of Economic Perspectives 159 Lucas RJ Lectures on Growth Theory (2002) Luhmann N Ausdifferenzierung des Rechts: Beiträge zur Rechtssoziologie und Rechtstheorie (1981) Luhman N ‘The Self-Reproduction of Law and its Limits’ in G Teubner (ed) Dilemmas of Law in the Welfare State (1986) 111 Lukes S Émile Durkheim. His Life and Work: A Historical and Critical Study (1975) M McDonnell PJ ‘US Votes Could Sway Mexico’s Next Election’ (1999) 15 February Los Angeles Times A1 MacIntyre A Whose Justice? Which Rationality? (1988) McIntyre DE & RE Dorrington ‘Trends in the Distribution of South African Health Care Expenditure’ (1990) 78 SAMJ 125 Macneil I ‘Economic Analysis of Contractual Relations’ in P Burrows & CG Veljanovski (eds) The Economic Approach to Law (1981) 61 Maddison A The World Economy: A Millennial Perspective (2002) Maklem P ‘Constitutional Ropes of Sand or Justiciable Guarantees? Social Rights in a New South African Constitution’ (1992) 141 Univ of Pennsylvania LR 1 Malan N ‘Civil Society and the Right to have Access to Social Security in South Africa’ (2004) Unpublished Research Paper, RAU: Johannesburg Margolis J ‘The Rights of Man’ (1978) 4 Social Theory and Practice 423 Marshall TH ‘On Citizenship and Social Class’ in Class, Citizenship and Social Development (1964) 28 Marx K & F Engels The Communist Manifesto (1848) May J Poverty and Inequality in South Africa: Report Prepared for the Office of the Executive Deputy President and the Inter-Ministerial Committee for Poverty and Inequality (PIR Report) (1998) Melnick RS Between the Lines: Interpreting Welfare Rights (1994) Meyerson D Rights Limited (1997) Minow M ‘Just Education: An Essay for Frank Michelman’ (2004) 39 Tulsa LR 547 Michel S Children’s Interests/Mothers’ Rights: The Shaping of America’s Child Care Policy (1999) Michelman FI ‘Foreword: On Protecting the Poor through the Fourteenth Amendment’ (1969) 83 Harv LR 7 Bibliography 301 3 0 2 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E Michelman FI ‘In Pursuit of “Constitutional Welfare Rights”: One View of Rawls’ Theory of Justice’ (1973) 121 U Pa LR 962 Michelman FI ‘Welfare Rights in a Constitutional Democracy’ (1979) 3 Wash Univ LQ 659 Michelman FI ‘Justification (and Justifiability) of Law in a Contradictory World’ in J R Pennock & J W Chapman (eds) NOMOS XXVIII: Justification (1986) 71 Michelman FI ‘Foreword: Traces of Self-Government’ (1986) 100 Harv LR 4 Michelman FI ‘Possession vs. Distribution’ in the Constitutional Idea of Property’ (1987) 72 Iowa LR 1319 Michelman FI ‘Law’s Republic’ (1988) 97 Yale LJ 1493 Michelman FI ‘Conceptions of Democracy in American Constitutional Argument: Voting Rights’ (1989) 41 Fla LR 443 Michelman FI ‘Family Quarrel’ (1996) 17 Cardozo LR 1163 Michelman FI ‘Morality, Identity and ‘Constitutional Patriotism’’ (1999) 76 Denv U LR 1009 Michelman FI ‘“Democracy-Based Resistance” to a Constitutional Right of Social Citizenship: A Comment on Forbath’ (2001) 69 Fordham LR 1893 Michelman FI ‘The Problem of Constitutional Interpretive Disagreement: Can “Discourse of Application” Help?’ in M Aboulafai et al Habermas and Pragmatism (2002) 113 Miller AO (ed) A Christian Declaration on Human Rights: Theological Studies of the World Alliance of Reformed Churches (1977) Mokyr J The Lever of Riches (1990) Mollendorf D ‘Reasoning about Resources: Soobramoney and the Future of Economic Rights Claims’ (1998) 14 SAJHR 327 Moltmann J The Experiment Hope (1975) Moltmann J On Human Dignity: Political Theology and Ethics (1984) Moltmann J God for a Secular Society: The Public Relevance of Theology (1999) Mongiovi G ‘Distributive Justice: An Economist’s Perspective’ (2004) 13 The Good Society 45 Morton M & F Morton Chocolate: An Illustrated History (1986) Moskop J ‘Rawslian Justice and a Human Rights to Health Care’ (1983) 8(4) Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 329 Mostert H ‘Liberty, Social Responsibility and Fairness in the Context of Constitutional Property Protection and Regulation’ in H Botha, AJ van der Walt & J van der Walt (eds) Rights and Democracy in a Transformative Constitution (2004) 131 Mudge LS The Church as Moral Community: Ecclesiology and Ethics in Ecumenical Debate (1998) Mureinik E ‘Beyond a Charter of Luxuries: Economic Rights in the Constitution’ (1992) 8 SAJHR 464 N Nedelsky J ‘Reconceiving Rights as Relationship’ (1993) 1 Review of Constitutional Studies 1 Newman KS, No Shame in My Game: The Working Poor in the Inner City (1999) Niebuhr H The Responsible Self. An Essay in Christian Moral Philosophy (1978) North DC ‘Transaction Costs, Institutions, and Economic History’ (1984) 140 Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics 7 North DC Institutions, Institutional Change, and Economic Performance (1990) North DC ‘Institutions’ (1991) 5 Journal of Economic Perspectives 97 North DC ‘Five Propositions about Institutional Change’ in J Knight & I Sened (ed) Explaining Social Institutions (1995) 15 Novak WJ The People’s Welfare: Law and Regulation in Nineteenth-Century America (1996) Nozick R Anarchy, State, and Utopia (1974) Nussbaum MC ‘Capabilities, Human Rights and the Universal Declaration’ in B H Weston & S P Marks (eds) The Future of International Human Rights (1999) 25 Nussbaum MC Women and Human Development – The Capabilities Approach (2000) Nussbaum MC ‘The Enduring Significance of John Rawls’ (2001) The Chronicle of Higher Education B7 O O’Connor JS ‘Gender, Class and Citizenship in the Comparative Analysis of Welfare State Regimes: Theoretical and Methodological Issues’ (1993) 44 British J of Sociology 501 Olsen M The Rise and Decline of Nations: Economic Growth, Stagflation, and Social Rigidities (1982) Olsen FE ‘The Myth of State Intervention in the Family’ (1985) 18 University of Michigan J of Law Reform 835 Olson M ‘Big Bills left on the Sidewalk: Why Some Nations are Rich, and Others Poor’ in S Knack (ed) Democracy, Governance and Growth (2003) 29 Orloff AS ‘Gender and the Social Rights of Citizenship: The Comparative Analysis of Gender Relations and Welfare States’ (1993) 58 American Sociological Rev 303 P Packard R White Plague, Black Labor: Tuberculosis and the Political Economy of Health and Disease in South Africa (1989) Pavetti LD The Dynamics of Welfare and Work: Exploring the Process by Which Young Women Work Their Way Off Welfare (1993) unpublished PhD dissertation, JFK School of Government, Harvard University Peters AAG ‘Law as Critical Discussion’ in G Teubner (ed) Dilemmas of Law in the Welfare State (1986) 250 Pieterse M ‘Beyond the Welfare State: Globalisation of Neo-liberal Culture and the Constitutional Protection of Social and Economic Rights in South Africa’ (2003) 14 Stellenbosch LR 3 Pieterse E & M van Donk ‘The Politics of Socio-Economic Rights in South Africa. Ten Years after Apartheid’ (2004) 5:5 ESR Review 12 Pillay K ‘Implementation of Grootboom: Implications for the Enforcement of Socio-Economic Rights’ (2002) 6 Law, Democracy & Development 255 Pizzigati S ‘The Left and the Rich’ Paper presented at the Global Left Forum, New York City (2005) Pizzigati S Greed and Good (2005) Pope SJ (ed) The Ethics of Aquinas (2002) Popper KR The Logic of Science (1959) Popper KR The Poverty of Historicism (1961) Popper KR ‘Towards a Rational Theory of Tradition’ in KR Popper (ed) Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge (1992) 120 Posner RA Overcoming Law (1995) Posner RA ‘Values and Consequences: An Introduction to Economic Analysis of Law’ (1998) Chicago Law & Economics Working Paper no 53 Price M Health Policy and Planning (1986 ) Price M ‘Health Care as an Instrument of Apartheid Policy in South Africa’ (1986) 1 Health Policy and Planning 158 Priest G & W Klein ‘The Selection of Disputes for Litigation’ (1984) 13 J of Legal Studies 1 Bibliography 303 3 0 4 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E Q Quint PE ‘The Constitutional Guarantees of Social Welfare in the Process of German Unification’ (1999) 47 Am J Comp L 303 R Radin MJ & FI Michelman ‘Pragmatist and Poststructuralist Critical Legal Practice’ (1991) 139 U Pa LR 1019 Rasmussen LL Moral Fragments and Moral Community: A Proposal for Church in Society (1993) Rawls J Political Liberalism (1996) Rawls J ‘Preface for the French Edition of A Theory of Justice’ in Samuel Freeman (ed) Collected Papers (1999) 415 Rees RM ‘Bite-Sized Marketing: Candy Bars’ in A Szogyi (ed) Chocolate: Food of the Gods (1997) 125 Reich CA ‘The “New Property’’’ (1964) 73 Yale LJ 733 Reich CA ‘Individual Rights and Social Welfare: The Emerging Legal Issues’ (1965) 74 Yale LJ 1245 Reich CA ‘The Global Drug Gap’ (2000) 287 Science 1979 Resnik D ‘Developing Drugs for the Developing World: An Economic, Legal, Moral and Political Dilemma’ (2001) 1 Developing World Bioethics 11 Rhodes RP Health Care Politics, Policy and Distributive Justice (1992) Richardson N ‘Ethics of Character and Community’ in C Villa-Vicencio and J de Gruchy (eds) Doing Ethics in Context. South African Perspectives (1994) 89 Robra M Ökumenische Sozialethik (1994) Rodrik D, A Subramanian et al ‘Institutions Rule: The Primacy of Institutions over Geography and Integration in Economic Development’ (2002) NBER Working Paper 9305 Romer PM ‘The Origins of Endogenous Growth’ (1994) Journal of Economic Perspectives 8 Rorty R Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (1980) Rorty R Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (1989) Rorty R Truth and Progress (1998) Roosevelt FD ‘Objectives of the Administration’ (June 8, 1934) in The Public Papers and Addresses of Franklin D Roosevelt (1938) vol 3 291 Roux T ‘Legitimating Transformation: Political Resource Allocation in the South African Constitutional Court’ (2003) 10 Democratization 92 Ross T ‘The Rhetoric of Poverty: Their Immorality, Our Helplessness’ (1991) 79 Georgetown Law Journal 1499 S Sable CF & WH Simon ‘Destabilisation Rights: How Public Law Litigation Succeeds’ (2004) 117 Harvard LR 1016 Sachs A ‘Enforcement of Social and Economic Rights’ Speech at London School Economics Feb 27 2000 Sager LG ‘Justice in Plain Clothes: Reflections on the Thinness of Constitutional Law’ (1993) 88 Nw U LR 410 Sala-i-Martin X ‘The World Distribution of Income’ (2002) NBER Working Paper 8933 Samuelson PA ‘Some Uneasiness with the Coase Theorem’ (1993) 7 Japan and the World Economy 1 Sandel MJ Democracy’s Discontent: America in Search of a Public Philosophy (1996) Sandel MJ Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (1998) Schachter O ‘Human Dignity as a Normative Concept’ (1983) 77 Am J of Int Law 848 Schachter O ‘Human Dignity as a Value – Part I’ (1999) 14 Public Law 682 Schachter O ‘Human Dignity as a Foundational Value of our Constitutional Order’ (2000) 16 SAJHR 193 Schaeffer J ‘WARC’s Historic Commitments to Justice and Human Rights’ (1998) 48 Reformed World 63 Schauer F ‘Judging in a Corner of the Law’ (1988) 61 Southern California LR 1717 Schauer F Playing by the Rules: A Philosophical Examination of Rule-Based Decision-making in Law and in Life (1991) Scheppele KL ‘A Realpolitik Theory of Social Rights’ (2004) 82 Tex LR 1921 Schultz V ‘Life’s Work’ (2000) 100 Col LR 1881 Sen A Choice, Welfare and Measurement (1982) Sen A The Penalties of Unemployment (1997) Banca D’Italia Working Paper No 307 Sen A ‘The Possibility of Social Choice’ (1999) 89 American Economic Review 349 Sen A Development as Freedom (1999) Sen A The Penalties of Unemployment (1997) Banca D’Italia Working Paper No 307 Sened I ‘The Emergence of Individual Rights’ in J Knight & I Sened (ed) Explaining Social Institutions (1995) 161 Shapiro M & A Stone Sweet On Law, Politics, and Judicialization (2002) Singer JW ‘The Player and the Cards: Nihilism and Legal Theory’ (1984) 94 Yale LJ 1 Singer P (ed) A Companion to Ethics (2002) Skocpol T Protecting Soldiers and Mothers: The Political Origins of Social Policy in the United States (1992) Sloth-Nielsen J ‘The Right to Social Services, the Right to Social Security, and the Primary Prevention of Child Abuse in the Aftermath of Grootboom’ (2001) 17 SAJHR 210 Smit DJ ‘Die Droom van Bybelse Geregtigheid’ (1985) 15 Scriptura 51 Smit DJ ‘Paradigms of Radical Grace’ in C Villa-Vicencio (eds) On Reading Karl Barth in South Africa (1988) 33 Smit DJ ‘Die Bergrede en Christelike Etiek’ in CW Burger et al (eds) Riglyne vir Prediking oor die Bergrede (1990) 34 Smit DJ ‘Die Bergrede in die Geskiedenis’ in CW Burger et al (eds) Riglyne vir Prediking oor die Bergrede (1990) 11 Smit DJ ‘Oor die Prediking van Regverdiging en Reg’ in BA Müller et al (eds) Riglyne vir Prediking oor Regverdiging en Reg. Woord teen die Lig III/3 (1993) 1 Smit DJ and JL De Villiers ‘Hoe Christene in Suid-Afrika by Mekaar Verby Praat ... Oor Vier Morele Spreekwyses in die Suid-Afrikaanse Kerklike Konteks’ (1994) 15 Skrif en Kerk 228 Smit DJ ‘Oor die Unieke Openbare Rol van die Kerk’ (1996) 36 Tydskrif vir Geesteswetenskappe 190 Smit DJ ‘Oor die Kerk as ‘n Unieke Samelewingsverband’ (1996) 36 Tydskrif vir Geesteswetenskappe 119 Smit DJ ‘Reformed Ethics and Economic Justice’ (1996) 37 Nederduitse Gereformeerde Teologiese Tydskrif 438 Smit DJ ’Oor die Kerk as Unieke Samelewingsverband’ (1996) Tydskrif vir Geesteswetenskappe 119 Smit DJ ’Oor die Unieke Openbare Rol van die Kerk’ (1996) Tydskrif vir Geesteswetenskappe 190 Smit DJ ‘Seeing Things Differently – On Prayer and Politics’ in L Holness & RK Wüstenberg (eds) Theology in Dialogue: The Impact of the Arts, Humanities, and Science on Contemporary Religious Thought: Essays in Honor of John W de Gruchy (2002) 271 Smit DJ ‘Liberty/Freedom’ in N Lossky et al (eds) Dictionary of the Ecumenical Movement (2002) Smit DJ ‘On Learning to See? A Reformed Perspective on the Church and the Poor’ in P Couture & BJ Miller-McLemore (eds) Suffering, Poverty, and HIV-AIDS (2003) 55 Smit DJ ‘Oor die God wat Ons Roep’ in Handelinge van die NGK in SA (Wes- en Suid-Kaapland) (2003) H99 Smit DJ ‘Openbare Getuienis en Publieke Teologie Vandag?’ (2003) 82 Scriptura 39 Smit DJ ‘Oor die Kerk en Maatskaplike Uitdagings in Ons Land’ (2004) 45 Nederduitse Gereformeerde Teologiese Tydskrif 350 Bibliography 305 3 0 6 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E Smit DJ ‘The Impact of the Church in South Africa after the Collapse of the Apartheid Regime’ in K Bediako et al (eds) A New Day Dawning: African Christians living the Gospel (2004) 128 Smit DJ ‘Theologische Ansätze für kirchliches Engagement in Fragen der Globalisierung - Reformierte Perspektiven aus dem Südlichen Afrika’ 2004 Ökumenische Rundschau 160 Smith A The Wealth of Nations (1937) Smith A An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations (1950) Smith JF ‘Vote Denied to Mexicans Living Abroad’ (1999) 2 July Los Angeles Times A1 Smith RKM Textbook in International Human Rights (2003) Simitis S ‘Juridification of Labor Relations’ in G Teubner (ed) Juridification of Social Spheres (1987) 113 Soifer A ‘The Paradox of Paternalism and Laissez-Faire Constitutionalism: United States Supreme Court, 1888-1921’ (1987) 5 Law & History Review 252 Spalter-Roth R Making Work Pay: The Real Employment Opportunities of Single Mothers Participating in the AFDC Program (1994) Spragens T ‘Review Essay: Justice, Consensus, and Boundaries: Assessing Political Liberalism’ (2003) 31 Political Theory 589 Stone RH Reinhold Niebuhr: Prophet to Politicians (1981) Streak J & J Wehner ‘Children’s Socio-Economic Rights in the South African Constitution: Towards a Framework for Monitoring Implementation’ in E Coetzee & J Streak (eds) Monitoring Child Socio- Economic Rights in South Africa: Achievements and Challenges (2004) 50 Stern L ‘Opportunity and Health Care: Criticims and Suggestions’ (1983) 8(4) Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 339 Stewart RB & CR Sunstein ‘Public Programs and Private Rights’ (1982) 95 Harv LR 1195 Steyn LC ‘Regsbank en Regsfakulteit’ (1967) 30 THRHR 101 Stiglitz JE ‘Principal and Agent’ in J Eatwell, M Milgate & P Newman (eds) The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics (1987) 966 Sunstein CR ‘On Property and Constitutionalism’ (1991) Chicago Law and Economics Working Paper no 3 Sunstein CR ‘Social and Economic Rights? Lessons from South Africa’ (2001) Chicago Law and Economics Working Paper no 124 Sunstein CR ‘The Second Bill of Rights: The Last Great Speech of Franklin Delano Roosevelt and America’s Unfinished Pursuit of Freedom’ (prelim draft 26 July 2003) Sunstein CR The Second Bill of Rights: FDR’s Unfinished Revolution and Why We Need It More than Ever (2004) T Tanzi V ‘The Changing Role of the State in the Economy’ (1997) IMF Working Paper WP/97/114 Tanzi V ‘The Role of the State and the Quality of the Public Sector’ (2000) IMF Working Paper WP/00/36 Taylor MCE Erring: A Postmodern A/theology (1984) Trengove W ‘Judicial Remedies for Violations of Socio-Economic Rights’ (1999) 1 ESR Rev 8 Teubner G ‘The Transformation of Law in the Welfare State’ in G Teubner (ed) Dilemmas of Law in the Welfare State (1986) 3 Teubner G ‘Juridification Concepts, Aspects, Limits, Solutions’ in G Teubner (ed) Juridification of Social Spheres (1987) 16 Toebes BCA The Right to Health as a Human Right in International Law (1999) Torrance TF Karl Bath: An Introduction to his Early Theology, 1910-1931 (1960) Townsend P et al The Black Report and the Health Divide (1990) Tracy D The Analogical Imagination. Christian Theology and the Culture of Pluralism (1981) Tushnet M ‘State Action, Social Welfare Rights, and the Judicial Role: Some Comparative Observations’ (2002) 3 Chi J Intl L 435 Tushnet M ‘Strong Rights, Weak Courts’ (2004) 82 Tex LR 1895 V Van Blerk A ‘The Irony of Labels’ (1982) 99 SALJ 365 Van Blerk A Judge and Be Judged (1988) Van den Brink G Een Publieke Zaak. Theologie tussen Geloof en Wetenskap (2004) Van der Berg S & R Burger ‘Social Delivery in South Africa’ (2003) Stellenbosch Report prepared for the CDE Van der Westhuizen J ‘The Human Rights Debate in South Africa’ in K Nürnberger (ed) A Democratic Vision for South Africa. Political Realism and Christian Response (1991) 471 Van der Walt AJ ‘A South African Reading of Frank Michelman’s Theory of Social Justice’ in H Botha, A van der Walt & J van der Walt (eds) Rights and Democracy in a Transformative Constitution (2004) 163 Van Marle K ‘Love, Law and the South African Community: Critical Reflections on “Suspect Intimacies” and “Immanent Subjectivity”’ in H Botha, A van der Walt & J van der Walt (eds) Rights and Democracy in a Transformative Constitution (2004) 231 Van Marle K ‘‘‘No Last Word” – Reflections on the Imaginary Domain, Dignity and Intrinsic Worth’ (2002) Stell LR 299 Van Marle K ‘Revisiting the Politics of Post-Apartheid Constitutional Interpretation’ (2003) TSAR 549 Van Marle K ‘‘‘The Capabilities Approach”, “The Imaginary Domain”, and “Asymmetrical Reciprocity”: Feminist Perspectives on Equality and Justice’ (2003) 11 Feminist Legal Studies 255 Van Parijs P Real Freedom for All (1995) Van Rensburg HCJ ‘South African Health Care in Change’ (1991) 22 SA Journal of Sociology 1 Van Rensburg HCJ Health Care in South Africa: Structure and Dynamics (1992) Van Rensburg HCJ ‘Health and Health Care in South Africa in Transition: A Macro Perspective’ (1999) 31 Acta Academica 1 Van Rensburg HCJ & SR Benatar ‘The Legacy of Apartheid in Health and Health Care’ (1993) 24 SA Journal of Sociology 99 Van Rensburg HCJ & Fourie A ‘Privatisation of South African Health Care: In Whose Interest?’ (1988) 11 Curationis 1 Van Rensburg HCJ & C Ngwena ‘Health and Health Care in South Africa against an African Background’ in WC Cockerham (ed) The Blackwell Companion to Medical Sociology (2001) 365 Villa-Vicencio C A Theology of Reconstruction – Nationbuilding and Human Rights (1992) Voss G et al ‘Menschenwürde neu Buchstabieren’ (2000) 55 Una Sancta - Zeitschrift für ökumenische Begegnung 97 W Wacks R ‘Judges and Injustice’ (1984) 101 SALJ 266 Waldron J Liberal Rights: Collected Papers 1981-1991 (1993) Walshe P ‘Christianity and the Anti-apartheid struggle: The Prophetic Voice within Divided Churches’ in R Elphick & R Davenport (eds) Christianity in South Africa. A Political, Social and Cultural History (1997) 383 Walzer M ‘Philosophy and Democracy’ (1981) 9 Pol Theory 379 Ward G (ed) The Postmodern God: A Theological Reader (1998) Weingärtner E ‘Human Rights’ in N Lossky et al (eds) Dictionary of the Ecumenical Movement (2002) 548 Bibliography 307 3 0 8 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E Welker M ‘Security of Expectations’ (1986) 66 Journal of Religion 237 Welker M ‘Dynamiken der Rechtsentwicklung in den biblischen Überlieferungen’ in A Aarnio (ed) Rechtsnorm und Rechtswirklichkeit: Festschrift für Werner Krawietz zum 60. Geburtstag (1993) 779 Welker M ‘Moral, Recht und Ethos in evangelisch-theologischer Sicht’ in W Härle & R Preul (eds) Ethik und Recht (2002) 67 Wellman C ‘The Proliferation of Rights: Moral Progress or Empty Rhetoric?’ in L Gearon (ed) Human Rights & Religion (2002) 368 Williams L ‘The Ideology of Division: Behavior Modification Welfare Reform Proposals’ (1992) 102 Yale L J 719 Williams L Decades of Distortion: The Right’s 30-Year Assault on Welfare (1997) Williams L ‘Welfare Law and Legal Entitlements: The Social Roots of Poverty’ in D Kairys (ed) The Politics of Law: A Progressive Critique (1998) 569 Williamson OE ‘Contract Analysis: The Transaction Cost Approach’ in P Burrows & CG Veljanovski (eds) The Economic Approach to Law (1981) 39 Wilson S ‘Taming the Constitution: Rights and Reform in the South African Education System’ (2004) 20 SAJHR 418 Wilson WJ When Work Disappears: The World of the New Urban Poor (1996) Winfield RD The Just Economy (1990) Witte J ‘The Study of Law and Religion: An Apologia and Agenda’ (1988) Ministry and Mission 14 Wogaman JP Christian Moral Judgment (1988) Wogaman JP Christian Perspectives on Politics (2000) Y Yergin D & J Stanislaw The Commanding Heights (1998) Yoon YH, R Spalter-Roth & M Baldwin Unemployment Insurance: Barriers to Access for Women and Part-Time Workers (1995) Yuval- Davis N ‘Women, Citizenship and Difference’ (1997) 57 Feminist Rev 4 Z Zucker R Democratic Distributive Justice (2002) Zucker R ‘Democracy and Economic Justice’ Paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Political Science Association 23 August 2003 Zucker R ‘On the Future of the Justice Debates’ (2004) 13 The Good Society 67 Cases Alexkor Ltd and Another v Richtersveld Community and Others 2004 (5) SA 460 (CC) 210 Atkinson v Van Wyk and Another 1999 (1) SA 1080 (LCC) 203 August and Another v Electoral Commission and Others 1999 (3) SA 1 (CC) 143, 165 B v Minister of Correctional Services 1997 (6) BCLR 789 (C) 194, 195 Baartman v Port Elizabeth Municipality 2004 (1) SA 560 (SCA) 26 Bergboerdery v Makgoro 2000 (4) SA 575 (LCC) 203 Bernstein v Bester 1996 (2) SA 751 (CC) 142 Brink v Kitshoff NO 1996 (4) SA 197 (CC 152 Connors v The United Kingdom 2005 (40) EHRR 189 161 Conradie v Hanekom and Another 1999 (4) SA 491 (LCC) 221, 222 Cooper v Laupheimer 316 F Supp 264 (ED Pa 1970) 81 Cruzan v Director, Missouri Department of Health et al 497 US 261 (1990) 28 Dandridge v Williams 397 US 471 (1970) 85, 86, 88, 95 Dawood v Minister of Home Affairs; Shalabi v Minister of Home Affairs; Thomas v Minister of Home Affairs 2000 (3) SA 936 (CC) 142,143 Dandridge v Williams 397 US 471 (1970) 9 DeShaney v Winnebago County Dept of Social Services 489 US 189 (1989) 73, 98 Douglas v California 372 US 353 (1963) 87, 88 Eldridge v British Columbia (Attorney General) (1997) 151 DLR (4th) 577 (SC) 163, 163 Ex parte Chairperson of the Constitutional Assembly 1996 (4) SA 744 (CC) 38 Ex parte Geldenhuys 1926 OPD 155 212 Ferreira v Levin NO 1996 (1) SA 984 (CC) 148 Fose v Minister of Safety and Security 1997 (3) SA 786 (CC) 37 Gideon v Wainwright 372 US 335 (1963) 88 Goldberg v Kelly 397 US 254 (1970) 9, 12, 79, 82, 83, 84, 85, 242 Gosselin v Quebec (Attorney General) 2002 SCC 84 221 DLR (4th) 141, 151, 152, 153, 155, 156, 157, 158, 160 Government of the Republic of South Africa v Grootboom 2001 (1) SA 46 (CC) 3, 18, 26, 27, 28, 31, 33, 35, 54, 143, 144, 148, 154, 155, 158, 159, 160, 161, 164, 165, 192, 193 Griffin v Illinois 351 US 12 (1956) 8 Hlatshwayo v Hein 1999 (2) SA 834 (LCC) 205 Hagans v Lavine 415 US 528 (1974) 79 Harksen v Lane NO and Others 1998 (1) SA 300 (CC) 143, 144, 153 Harper v Virginia Board of Elections 383 US 663 (1966) 8, 87 Hoffman v SAA 2000 (11) BCLR 1211 (CC) 151 Holley v Lavine 553 F2d 845 (2d Cir 1977) 81 In re Jobes 529 A2d 434 (NJ S Ct 1987) 28 In re Macleantown Residents Association: Re Certain Erven and Commonage in Macleantown 1996 (4) SA 1272 (LCC) 206, 207 JA v Riti 377 F Supp 1046 (DFNJ 1974) 81 Jackson v City of Joliet 715 F 2d 1200 (7th Cir) (1983) 7 Jaftha v Schoeman and Others; Van Rooyen v Stoltz and Others 2005 (1) BCLR 78 (CC) 143, 160 Jooste v Botha 2002 (2) BCLR 187 (T) 29 3 1 0 T H E O R I E S O F S O C I A L A N D E C O N O M I C J U S T I C E Karabo and Others v Kok and Others 1998 (1) SA 1014 (LCC) 205 Khosa v Minister of Social Development 2004 (6) SA 505 (CC) 18, 25, 33, 34, 150, 151, 161, 162, 163, 164, 166 King v Smith 392 US (1968) 79, 80, 95 Khuzwayo v Dludla [2000] 4 All SA 329 (LCC) 203 Landbou Navorsingsraad v Klaasen LCC Case 83R/01 (unreported 29 October 2001) 21, 222 Lategan v Koopman en Andere 1998 (3) SA 457 (LCC) 203 Law v Canada (Minister of Employment and Immigration) (1999) 170 DLR (4th) 153 Lewis v Martin 397 US 552 (1970) 81 Magodi and Others v Van Rensburg [2001] 4 All SA 485 (LCC) 204 Mahlangu and Another v Van Eeden and Another [2000] 3 All SA 321 (LCC) 203 Mahlangu v De Jager 1996 (3) SA 325 (LCC) 203, 205 Mashavha v President of the RSA & Others 2004 (12) BCLR 1243 (CC) 152 Maryland v Mathews 415 F Supp 1206 (DDC 1976) 81 Minister of Finance & Another v Van Heerden 2004 (11) BCLR 1125 (CC) 145 Minister of Health v Treatment Action Campaign 2002 (5) SA 721 (CC) 18, 24, 25, 29, 30, 31, 32, 33, 53, 54, 151, 154, 155, 159, 160, 165, 192, 193, 194 Minister of Home Affairs and Others v Watchenuka and Another 2004 (2) BCLR 120 (SCA) 150, 151, 153, 154 Minister of Land Affairs and Another v Slamdien and Others [1999] 1 All SA 608 (LCC); 1999 (4) BCLR 413 (LCC) 208 Modderfontein Squatters v Modderklip Boerdery (Pty) Ltd 2004 (6) SA 40 (SCA) 18, 25, 33, 35 Muller v Oregon 208 US 412 (1908) 14 National Coalition for Gay & Lesbian Equality v Minister of Justice and Others 1999 (1) SA 6 (CC) 42, 143, 145, 146, 184 Nevada Department of Human Resources v Hibbs 123 S Ct 1972 (2003) 106 Nhlabati v Fick [2003] 2 All SA 323 (LCC) 3, 214 Nkosi and Another v Buhrmann 2002 (1) SA 372 (SCA) 213 Ntai and Others v Vereniging Town Council and Another 1953 (4) SA 579 (A) 211 Owens v Roberts 377 F Supp 45 (MD Fla 1974) 81 Pitout v Mbolane [2000] 2 All SA 377 (LCC) 203 Port Elizabeth Municipality v Various Occupiers 2005 (1) SA 217 (CC)3, 18, 27, 33, 34, 35, 150, 151 President of the Republic of South African and Another v Hugo 1997 (4) SA 1 (CC) 150 Prince v President of the Law Society of the Cape of Good Hope & Others 2002 (2) SA 794 (CC) 148 Prinsloo v Van der Linde 1997 (3) SA 1012 (CC) 152 R v Cambridge Health Authority, ex parte B [1995] 2 All ER 129 (CA) 27, 197 Richtersveld Community v Alexkor Ltd and Another 2000 (1) SA 337 (LCC) 208, 209 Rosado v Wyman 397 US 397 416-17 (1970) 81 Rothstein v Wyman 303 F Supp 339 (SD FNY 1969) 87 S v Makwanyane & Another 1995 (3) SA 391 (CC) 143, 145, 149, 150, 196 S v Mamabolo (E TV and Others Intervening) 2001 (3) SA 409 (CC) 144 San Antonio Independent School District v Rodriguez 411 US 1 (1973) 85, 88 Serole and Another v Pienaar 2000 (1) SA 328 (LCC) 205, 222 Shapiro v Thompson 394 US 618 (1969) 79, 81, 82, 87 Skhosana and Others v Roos t/a Roos se Oord and Others 2000 (4) SA 561 (LCC) 203, 205 Soobramoney v Minister of Health, KwaZulu-Natal 1998 (1) SA 765 (CC) 18, 25, 27, 28, 31, 32, 55, 144, 148, 149, 150, 194, 196, 197 The Social and Economic Rights Action Centre and the Centre for Economic and Social Rights v Nigeria Communication No 155/96 October 2001 (African Commission on Human and Peoples’ Rights) 143, 148 Tucker v Toia 371 NE 2d 449 (NY 1977) 11 Van Lare v Hurley 421 US 338 (1975) 81 Van Zyl NO v Maarman [2000] 4 All SA 212 (LCC) 203 Williams v Dandridge 297 F Supp 450 469 (D Md 1968) 85 Cases 311 Legislation and Policy Documents Advisory Council on Unemployment Compensation, Report and Recommendations (Washington, DC: US Government Printing Office 1995) 247 African Charter of Human and People’s Rights (1981) 148 Choice on Termination of Pregnancy Act 92 of 1996 191 Constitution of the Republic of South Africa Act 200 of 1993 179, 199, 208 Constitution of the Republic of South Africa Act 108 of 1996 164, 165, 167, 169, 179, 190, 192, 193, 203, 235 Constitucion Politica de los Estados Unidos Mexicanos, art 30 (amended 1996) 253 Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination Against Women (1979) 183 Convention of the Rights of the Child (2002) 183 Department of Health National HIV and Syphilis Sero-Prevalence Survey of Women Attending Ante-Natal Clinics in South Africa in 2001 (2003) 193 Department of Health Operational Plan for Comprehensive HIV and AIDS Care, Management and Treatment for South Africa (2003) 193 Dutch Reformed Church in Africa ‘Transition and Poverty’ (1990) 2/90 (Supplement) DRCA Action Economic Justice in South Africa : A Pastoral Statement (1999) 231 Evangelical Church in Germany and the German Bishops’ Conference For a Future Founded on Solidarity and Justice: A Statement of the Evangelical Church in Germany and the German Bishops’ Conference on the Economic and Social Situation in Germany (1997) 231 Extension of Security of Tenure Act 62 of 1997 203, 205, 210, 212, 213, 220, 221, 222, 223 Gluckman Commission Report of the National Health Services Commission (1944) 186, 187 International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1966) 183, 183, 168, 169, 183 Land Affairs General Amendment Act 51 of 2001 214 Land Reform (Labour Tenants) Act 3 of 1996 203 Land Restitution and Reform Laws Amendment Act 18 of 1999 206 MarketResearch.com Academic The Chocolate Market (2001) Web publication www.academic.marketresearch.com/product/print/default.asp 283, 284, 285 Medical Schemes Act 131 of 1998 191 Medical Research Council Changing Health in South Africa: Towards New Perspectives in Research (1991) 188 Medicines and Related Substances Act 90 of 1997 191 National Compensation Survey: Occupational Wages in the United States, 2001 288 National Health Act 63 of 1977 179, 189 National Health Act 61 of 2003 179, 191, 192 Natives Land Act 28 of 1913 208 Nelson Mandela Foundation/HSRC Report Emerging Voices: A Report on Education in South African Rural Communities (2002) 59 Prevention of Illegal Eviction from and Unlawful Occupation of Land Act 19 of 1998 26, 146 Public Health Act 1919 79, 185 Restitution of Land Rights Act 2 of 1994 199, 203, 206, 208, 220, 223, 224 RES Testimony on Human Rights (1983) 223 Social Assistance Act 59 of 1992 26 Social Security Act 1935 (US) 79, 84 Staff of House Committee on Ways and Means Background Material and Data on Programs. Within the Jurisdiction of the Committee on Ways and Means (1996) 104th Cong 2d Sess 246 The Confession of Belhar (1986) 129, 225 The Kairos Document: Challenge to the Church: a Theological Comment on the Political Crisis in South Africa (1985) 129 United Nations General Comment No 3 (Fifth session, 1990) The Nature of States Parties Obligations (art 2(1) of the Covenant), UN doc E/1991/23 163 United Nations General Comment (2003) Human Security Now, presented to the United Nations Secretary-General, Kofi Annan on 1 May 2003 57 United Nations General Assembly (1948) Universal Declaration of Human Rights adopted 10 December 1948 168 US Dept of Justice, Immigration and Naturalization Service, 1996 Statistical Yearbook of the Immigration and Naturalization Service (1997) 253 White Paper on Transformation of the Health System in South Africa (1997) 179, 190 World Bank World Development Report 2002. Building Institutions for Markets (2002) 46 World Health Organisation Global Strategy for Health for All by the Year 2000 (1981) 190 Legislation and Policy Documents 313 Index Anti-paternalism 6, 13 Children 29, 77, 80, 85 Citizenship 153, 240, 249, 280 Civic Republicanism 7, 74, 98, 100 Civil society / NGOs 33, 129, 131, 135, 177, 237 Communitarianism 34, 280 Critical theories 6, 199, 227, 230, 239 Depoliticisation 18, 21, 25, 36 Development economics 40, 51 Dignity-based theories 90, 92, 141, 143, 145, 152, 232 Directive principles 104 Due process-based theories 3, 242 Durkheim, Emile 108 Economic theory 4, 37, 41, 51, 52, 109, 168, 170, 256, 257, 261, 267, 274, 276, 285, 287 Egalitarian vs libertarian theories 180, 256, 270 Equality-based theories 2, 69, 87, 144, 153, 256, 260, 261 Fraser, Nancy 19 Fundamentalism 68 Hayek, Friedrich von 43, 51, 171 Health care 26, 27, 29, 151, 165, 179, 193, 194, 196 HIV/Aids 18, 19, 26, 30, 33, 58, 151, 192, 193, 194, 195 Homelessness and housing 26, 28, 33, 35, 58, 192, 199, 206, 208, 210 Institutional argument 32, 49, 61, 112, 175, 222 Institutional capacity 30, 31, 60, 93, 96, 103 Judicial review / overview 31, 32, 35, 49, 53, 154, 159, 160, 165 199, 206 Justiciability 93, 96, 103, 142 Klare, Karl 17, 49, 218 Labour rights / employment 89, 239, 240, 245, 251 Legal Realism 6, 8, 11, 12 Michelman, Frank 2, 9, 72, 73, 79, 86, 90, 98 Millennium Development Goals (UN) 58 Minimum / core rights 30, 85, 86, 155, 158, 160, 166, 168, 169, 183 Morality-based theories 57, 61, 115, 120, 261, 276 Needs-based theories 2, 86, 154 Negative vs positive rights 7, 48, 49, 108, 111, 149 New Deal 15, 73, 76, 84 New Institutional Economics 38, 43, 44, 49, 112 New Property 9, 82 Normality assumption 3, 241 Normative theories 39, 226, 276 Positive social science 37, 38, 39, 41, 52, 53, 54 Posner, Richard 7, 8 Poverty 9, 15, 19, 21, 60, 79, 241, 260 Progressive realization 47 Public choice theory 40, 41 Public vs private 32, 61, 65, 114, 240, 245 Race 77, 78, 188, 189, 208, 210 Rawls, John 74, 86, 90, 124, 171, 180, 258 Reich, Charles 2, 9, 12, 15, 82 Rhetoric 24, 25, 28, 33, 36, 244, 254 Roosevelt, Franklin D 8, 15 Sen, Amartya 60, 67, 172, 174 Social citizenship 89, 97, 101, 103, 105, 240, 249, 276 Social Darwinism 13 Sunstein, Cass 6, 9 Theological theory 62, 63, 64, 67, 69, 128, 133, 225 ‘Theory drag’ 3, 38, 39, 128, 214, 215, 225, 234 ‘Theory matters’ 3, 38, 39, 57, 128, 225, 226 Transformative Constitutionalism 17, 49, 50, 199, 214, 215, 218 War on Poverty 9, 15, 75, 78, 89 Welfare rights 9, 10, 75, 76, 78, 79, 82, 85, 100, 101, 105, 150, 239, 241, 246, 252 Index 315 Th eor ies o f So cia l an d E co no m ic J us tic e Theories of Social and Economic Justice T h eories of S ocial an d E con om ic Ju stice A J van d er W alt Edited by AJ van der Walt T he bulk of the contributions in Theories of Social and Economic Justice originated in a research project initiated by the Stellenbosch Institute for Advanced Study (STIAS) in 2002. STIAS hosted a workshop in July 2004 in which researchers from Law, Economics, Theology and Sociology participated, and some of the contributions at the workshop were subsequently reworked into chapters for this book. In addition, colleagues, both in South Africa and abroad, who had not participated in the workshop but whose recently published work on social and economic justice fitted in with the project extremely well, gave permission to re-publish their articles in the book. The book is based on the idea that the attainment of greater social and economic justice, specifically in the South African context, is strongly influenced by the implications and the coherence of various theories of social and economic justice. Furthermore, it is argued that the promotion and protection of social and economic justice need to be approached from different theoretical perspectives when considering different practical circumstances, contexts and dilemmas. One theoretical size simply does not fit all, as far as social and economic justice is concerned. The range of theoretical approaches represented in this book – legal, economic, theological and sociological – is testimony to the truly cross- and multi-disciplinary nature of the contributions. Apart from leading South African scholars in Law, Economics, Theology and Sociology, four contributions from American academics are included: Professors Gregory Alexander (Cornell Law School), William Forbath (University of Texas), Lucy Williams (Northeastern University), and Ross Zucker (Lander College). AJ van der Walt is professor in the Faculty of Law at Stellenbosch University and author of Constitutional Property Clauses: A Comparative Analysis (1999) and Constitutional Property Law (2005). He is also a co-editor, with H Botha and J van der Walt, of Rights and Democracy in a Transformative Constitution (2004, AFRICAN SUN MeDIA). THEORIES finaal Q5 2/8/05 9:15 Page 1 Preface Socio-Economic Rights in American Perspective: The Tradition of Anti-Paternalism in American Constitutional Thought The ‘Politics of Need Interpretation’ and the Adjudication of Socio-Economic Rights Claims in South Africa New Tools for the Constitutional Bench Social Justice and Theological Method A Not so Simple Justice: Frank Michelman on Social Rights, 1969 – Present The Just Community: Emile Durkheim on Liberalism and Society Theology and the Fulfillment of Social and Economic Rights: Some Theoretical Considerations The Value of Human Dignity in Interpreting Socio-Economic Rights The Fiscal Implications of Social and Economic Justice: An Overview of the Changing Theoretical Framework The Historical Development of the Modern South African Health-Care System: From Privilege to Egalitarianism Pro-Poor Court, Anti-Poor Outcomes: Explaining The Performance of the South African Land Claims Court On Social and Economic Justice in South Africa Today: A Theological Perspective on Theoretical Paradigms Beyond Labour Law’s Parochialism: A Re-envisioning of the Discourse of Redistribution Opening the Door to More Equality Bibliography Cases Legislation and Policy Documents Index Button1: work_dlwvfv2wsbh5zehbxzlfb2vcga ---- TRR 2013 8 DATA NEEDS AND AVAILABILITY Collecting the appropriate types of data in sufficient quantities for rigorous analysis is a challenge that pervades all of transportation planning. This section looks at five types of data that are needed for determining the EJ implications of a long-range plan, compar- ing what is currently available with what is ideally needed for both a base year and future years. The data types considered are the spa- tial distributions of race and income, the spatial distributions of trip ends, trip tables, network performance, and cost estimates of improvements. When any type of data are obtained, their accuracy should be questioned. Long-range plans, or metropolitan transportation plans (MTPs), forecast anywhere from 20 to 50 years into the future. Demo- graphics forecasts are known to be subject to much uncertainty (13), and the finer the level of data required (i.e., locations of retail busi- nesses instead of locations of total businesses) and the longer the amount of time between the base and forecast years, the more uncer- tainty there is. Hirschman details the assumptions in projections of demographics by race and ethnicity (14), and Smith and Nogle study projections of the Hispanic population and conclude that the errors tend to be larger for this group than for the total population (15). Spatial Distribution of Race and Income The decennial census provides information on the race of each per- son and the income level of each household at the block group level. For most MPOs, demographic forecasts output total residents and total employment by type in each zone or district, but they do not forecast the spatial distribution of race or income. Without predic- tions of the spatial distributions of race and income, the distributions in future years are typically assumed to be the same as those in the base year. A comparison of the 1990 and the 2000 census data for many regions shows that this assumption is a poor one, but there are few alternatives. Purvis describes the difficulty in obtaining predic- tions of race and income for EJ analyses, commenting that federal and state forecasts typically continue past trends (16 ). Spatial Distribution of Trip Ends In a growing region, keeping abreast of new developments (i.e., sub- divisions and shopping centers) can be a full-time job, and pre- dicting the location of development years into the future is nearly impossible. Despite the availability of data on existing develop- ments, trends, topography, and land use restrictions, the locations chosen by developers are not predictable with any degree of accu- racy. The uncertainty about future development is important not only for determining future trip tables but also for determining future Environmental Justice Analysis Challenges for Metropolitan Transportation Planning Jen Duthie, Ken Cervenka, and S. Travis Waller This research focuses on three major challenges of incorporating envi- ronmental justice into metropolitan transportation planning. The data needed are compared with the data currently available on the spatial distributions of race and income, the spatial distributions of trip ends, trip tables, network performance, and cost estimates of improvements. Several conflicting definitions of equity are offered, as are applications for each within the context of environmental justice. The importance of choosing a correct unit of analysis is discussed, with particular emphasis on how the geographic unit of analysis is a poor proxy for the group unit, which is theoretically required, as the analysis’s purpose is to compare performance measures across groups. The primary goal of this paper is to explore challenging topics such as these raising questions and con- cerns. The answers to the questions raised will differ depending on each implementing agency’s objectives and resources. In the 12 years since Executive Order 12898, Federal Actions to Address Environmental Justice in Minority Populations and Low- Income Populations (1), was issued, much progress has been made in formalizing environmental justice (EJ) analyses within transportation planning. However, as metropolitan planning organizations (MPOs) produce long-range plans approximately every 5 years, formal EJ analyses of these plans are still in their infancy. To date, most of the research on EJ analyses in transportation planning has focused on specific analysis techniques (2, 3) or the equity impacts of specific projects (4–7), modes (8–10), and fund- ing structures (11, 12). Although such discussions are of obvious importance, this paper focuses on three major challenges that have received limited attention in the context of long-range planning: 1. Collecting the needed data, 2. Coming to a consensus on how equity should be defined and applied in the context of EJ, and 3. Using an appropriate unit of analysis The goal of this paper is to explore these challenging topics, raising questions and concerns; it is not to offer specific recommendations to public agencies. The following sections are devoted to addressing the three challenges mentioned above, and the paper concludes with a summary and a discussion of research needs. J. Duthie, 6.506 ECJ Hall, and S. T. Waller, 6.204 ECJ Hall, Department of Civil, Architectural, and Environmental Engineering, University of Texas at Austin, 1 Uni- versity Station, C1761, Austin, TX 76011. K. Cervenka, North Central Texas Coun- cil of Governments, 616 Six Flags Drive, Centerpoint Two, Arlington, TX 76005. Corresponding author: J. Duthie, jduthie@mail.utexas.edu. Transportation Research Record: Journal of the Transportation Research Board, No. 2013, Transportation Research Board of the National Academies, Washington, D.C., 2007, pp. 8–12. DOI: 10.3141/2013-02 Duthie, Cervenka, and Waller 9 accessibility to important locations. Several MPOs compare access to critical nonwork locations, such as schools and health care facil- ities, by protected and unprotected classes. As residential and com- mercial developments sprawl, so do schools and hospitals. However, without more information, the locations of these facilities are assumed to remain unchanged in the future. Increased cooperation between transportation and land use planners and school and hospital admin- istrators could reduce the level of surprise at new developments. Even current year data can be difficult to work with in some cases because not all health care facilities accept low-income people, not every job is suited for every person, and not all children can attend their neighborhood school. Trip Tables Accurate trip tables are important for the many EJ performance mea- sures related to accessibility, as they can be used to compare travel times to employment and other critical locations. [A comprehensive overview of such measures has been presented previously (17 ).] If trip tables were available by minority and income classes, much more could be done to measure accessibility. Segmented trip tables would allow the analysis of selected links to determine how many people from each class will benefit from a particular roadway or transit proj- ect. Without this, accessibility measures must assume that the percent- age of trips between each origin–destination pair made by a specific class is equal to the percentage of residents at the origin that are a member of the class. This assumption is rather arbitrary and could be improved by the use of information from household survey data. A second issue with future-year trip tables related to EJ is the poten- tial to reinforce existing inequities. According to Deka, “if workers who live in predominantly low-income and minority areas have short commutes at present, computer models will predict a short commute for them in the future as well, regardless of their true commuting needs” (18). This observation implies that network improvements may be based on the paths where people currently are traveling, not on the paths where they would like to travel. By making it easier for them to travel on their current path, they are being helped with con- tinuing the status quo rather than helped with getting where they would like to go. This concern is much greater with gravity-based models than with models that use destination choice. Network Performance Measures of network performance based on the results from a travel model are limited mostly to expected volumes, delays, and travel times. As models are calibrated to expected conditions, the model re- sults, including EJ-related performance measures, are approximates of the expected performance. Unfortunately, this process leaves out one important measure of performance: reliability. Performance mea- sures that capture the reliability of travel times would aid not only EJ analysis but also other transportation analyses. The resulting perfor- mance measures may be misleading if average measures are used because two groups may have the same average time, but one group’s access may vary much more from day to day. Data collected from intelligent transportation systems can aid with the collection of the large amounts of data required to obtain an accurate representation of current reliability. Future reliability may be more difficult to discern, but as research is conducted on trends that have led to the current levels of reliability, the ability to predict future levels of reliability will be improved. Cost Estimates of Improvements As will be discussed in the following section, EJ can be defined in terms of the impacts (i.e., travel time changes) on each population or in terms of the funding spent on improving conditions for each popu- lation. To estimate equity in funding, accurate cost estimates must be obtained for each improvement specified in the long-range plan. The difficulties with this method are the assumptions made for inflation rates and the costs of construction in future years. Also, the MTP may specify categories of spending instead of specific projects, making the benefit to each population group impossible to discern. State-of-the-art travel models that rely on microsimulation to track activity patterns promise to alleviate some of these data issues. Household survey data could perhaps be used more extensively to synthesize trip tables and the behavior specific to each population group. There is, however, the danger that such tools will improve the precision of the results without improving the accuracy. The following section describes the various ways in which equity may be defined in the context of EJ. EQUITY This section reviews several definitions of equity presented in the literature, three main applications of equity in long-range planning, and multiple methods for approaching the time frame and scope of analysis. The purpose of this section is to stress that the calculation of performance measures is a futile effort unless it is certain what type of equity is achieved, because after the calculations are com- plete, there will be numbers that cannot provide a sense of whether or not an injustice has occurred. Defining Equity Reaching an agreement as to which type of equity should be applied in an EJ analysis is not easy, and all of the options should be weighed. More definitions of equity than can be concisely presented here can be found in the literature. Four types of equity most applicable to trans- portation planning are presented and are referred to here as “oppor- tunity,” “equality,” “market based,” and “basic needs.” FHWA does not provide clear guidance on how to define equity, so the decision is left up to the MPOs. Opportunity Equity of opportunity is most often defined as each person or group having equal access to the planning process and having their opin- ions taken into account in an equal manner. The first step that many MPOs take toward fulfilling the EJ requirements is outreach to the traditionally underserved populations. Outreach can take several forms, including hosting public meetings in protected areas at times of day convenient for working people, ensuring easy access to the meeting by nonautomobile modes of travel, and providing translators for people who are not fluent in English. Equality Equality—which is typically thought of as a synonym for equity— entails the comparison of performance measures with the goal of 10 Transportation Research Record 2013 providing equal benefits for each population. Within the context of equality, one can consider equal benefits in a future year or an equal change in benefits over time. As the needs and desires of people dif- fer, equity in benefits may be achieved even if the actual benefits received by each group are different. Equality can also be considered in terms of the allocation of funding. Market Based Market-based equity means “you get what you pay for.” Several studies have evaluated how well market-based equity is achieved in transportation financing (11, 12) by comparing how much a group pays in taxes and fees with the resources and benefits that it receives. Taylor (19) also refers to this as market equity; Litman (20), Khisty (21), and Lee (22) refer to this as horizontal equity. Basic Needs Meeting basic needs is a compromise between the first two types of equity. First, the basic needs of each person are met, and then any remaining resources and benefits are distributed according to mar- ket equity. Khisty describes it best as “bread for all, before butter for some” (21). Challenge of Defining Equity Deciding which type of equity to strive for does not, by itself, make the selection of plans or projects among alternatives straightforward. If Plan A offers each of two groups $10 in benefits and Plan B offers the first group $10 and the second group $15, should Plan A be cho- sen on the grounds of equity? Khisty uses a small network to demon- strate how the optimal network improvements differ depending on the type of equity considered (21). The guidance from FHWA on the distribution of funding and its impacts is conflicting. A memorandum issued in January 2000 states that one of the three basic principles of EJ is to “assure low-income and minority groups receive proportionate share of benefits” (23). However, the current FHWA policy, as stated on its website (24), is that beyond the requirement to mitigate disparate impacts, “there is no presumed distribution of resources to sustain compliance with the environmental justice provisions.” Applications of Equity Equity determinations are threefold, examining first the equity in public participation, then the equity in funding, and lastly the equity in impacts. Because the focus of this paper is on technical methods, this section looks primarily at equity in funding and equity in impacts. Giving each population group equal access to the planning pro- cess is extremely important; however, unlike funding and impacts, it is not easily measured by quantitative tools. First, it should be noted that equitable funding does not imply equitable impacts. For example, Group A and Group B could be allocated equal funds, but if Group A decides to use its funds to run a highway through the center of Group B’s community, the resulting impacts will likely be inequitable. The distribution of impacts and funding into the future is difficult to measure because MTPs cannot, because of their long time frame, specify projects in great detail. Much of the money allocated in MTPs goes toward programs that act as funding mechanisms for projects that will be specified at a later date. Some entries in the MTP, such as capacity improvements on a corridor, may contain more detail than other entries, such as a program for funding intelligent transporta- tion systems. Until the projects are selected, there is no accurate way of evaluating the impact that will be felt by each population. Any calculation of program benefits that occurs before the projects are selected will be a rough regional estimate and will be unsuited for a group-level analysis. It is similarly difficult to determine years in advance the distribution of funding among population groups, as it is not specified as such in the plan. Although future funding can be estimated, the exact amount of money available for a particular MTP is also not known with cer- tainty. Revenue from fuel taxes depends on vehicle usage and effi- ciency, and political pressures exist to keep them from rising with inflation. Toll roads may bring in another source of revenue, albeit an uncertain source, as their popularity increases. Private investment in toll roads is an increasingly enticing option for regions in need of upfront money for new projects. Money available for transit depends not only on fares but also on the political climate and public senti- ment. Despite all the funding uncertainty, however, if the planned funding is distributed equitably and the removed or additional fund- ing is removed or added equitably, then the final funding distribution should be equitable. Static Versus Changing Time Frames Perhaps the most controversial aspect of impact evaluation is the time frame considered. Impacts can be assessed in the future year or through the change in impacts from the base year to the future year. At the core of this debate is whether or not EJ should redress past injustices. For example, if the MTP improves travel times for Groups A and B by 10 min each, but Group A’s base year travel time is 30 min longer than Group B’s, is the MTP equitable? Most MPOs, by focusing on the change in measures during the planning period, would say “yes,” claiming that as long as their current and future actions affect each group proportionately, they are within the fed- eral guidelines. Although MPOs may be within their legal limits to evaluate impacts in this way, as long as disparities exist in trans- portation benefits and costs, sectors of the population will continue to believe that the system is not just. Equating future-year perfor- mance measures, however, has its problems, too. One issue with using future-year travel times as a performance measure is that some populations, particularly those with higher incomes, may choose a longer commute in return for other benefits, such as a larger house or better schools. It is unreasonable to try to equate such a popula- tion’s long commute time with the commute time of a lower-income population that lives in close proximity to its destinations. Scope of Analysis As stated above, the purpose of considering EJ in the MTP is to en- sure that no group is disproportionately adversely affected. Before an MPO can determine whether or not the plan is equitable, a deci- sion must be made as to whether each performance measure is going to be looked at individually or whether a holistic view will be taken in the analysis. Most practitioners and researchers would argue that the point of analyzing EJ in the MTP is so that the system can be evaluated as a whole; the total benefits, costs, and funding should be compared across groups. Despite this apparent consensus, it is not uncommon for an EJ analysis to present many types of perfor- mance measures without concluding whether or not a group is dis- proportionately adversely affected. This issue is more one of impact equity than funding equity, as combining monetary units is simpler and requires fewer value judgments than combining various impact measures. The difficulty in creating a system-level EJ determination is in how to combine the individual performance measure results. A survey of the population could tell the analyst which performance measures are the most important and allow the creation of a generalized utility term. One could make the problem even more difficult by allowing each sector of the population to have a different set of preferences. If each group is assumed to have the same transportation needs, then the evaluation of disparate impacts within programs or single perfor- mance measures is appropriate. If the needs of each group are dif- ferent, however, a system-level analysis is the only way to determine EJ results. To find out the needs of the EJ populations, some MPOs have formed task forces composed of representatives from each group. Other MPOs, fearing that an EJ task force will slow the plan- ning process without being truly representative of the traditionally underserved groups, have increased their public outreach efforts. Once the needs of each group are defined, the trick is to evaluate equity in terms of how well each group’s needs are met. If Group A is primarily concerned with pedestrian access to destinations and Group B cares about automobile commute times, an equity analysis would measure how well Group A’s need for better sidewalk con- nectivity is being met compared with how well Group B’s desire for increased freeway capacity is being fulfilled. This example also illus- trates a case in which impact equity will lead to funding inequity, because sidewalk connectivity is cheaper to provide than roadway capacity. Although a system-level equity analysis requires more thought and public input than evaluation of program-level or performance-measure disparities, it is much more intuitive and has the added benefit of ensuring that the transportation services pro- vided are actually meeting the needs of the public. Funding Equity at Federal and State Levels This paper focuses on equity related to EJ in long-range planning; however, the topic of equity brings much debate in other areas of transportation. Most notable is the discussion of equity in the distri- bution of federal funds to states. When states argue that they are not getting their fair share of funds, they are usually implying that they are the subjects of market inequity. Currently, the allocation of fed- eral funds from the Highway Trust Fund ensures a pseudo–market equity in which each state receives at least a 90.5% rate of return on the basis of its tax receipt contribution (11). The distribution of funding within states has also caused contro- versy. In recent years the Denver Regional Council of Governments has worked with the State of Colorado to remedy a market inequity in which the Denver metropolitan area was receiving $0.54 in funding for every $1 that it contributed (25). Washington State created a statewide Transportation Improvement Account to funnel gas tax rev- enue to urban areas after it was discovered that Seattle raised 51% of the state’s revenues and received only 39% in return (11). Tennessee, Arkansas, Ohio, and Alabama distribute portions of their transporta- tion funds evenly to each county in the state, regardless of the popu- lation and the need (11). It is argued that this type of geographic equity facilitates sprawl because of the spending of proportionally more money in rural areas. UNIT OF ANALYSIS EJ compliance determinations can be made by use of one of the fol- lowing units of analysis: individual, group, or geographic. The unit of analysis is the basis for the comparison of performance measures. Most equity analyses for applications other than EJ use the individual unit of analysis. For example, Levinson (26) uses the Gini coefficient to measure the equity of ramp metering, and Connors et al. (27) seek toll rates that maximize the Theil entropy index used to measure social welfare. In theory, EJ uses the group unit of analysis and compares the impacts across groups defined by race, ethnicity, and income. Because adequate data at the group level (i.e., trip tables disaggre- gated by group) are rarely available, most EJ analyses are done by the use of geographic units. There are, however, several problems with this approach. A traffic survey zone is defined as protected or unprotected on the basis of its percentage of minority or low-income residents. Such a classification accounts for neither the number of residents in a zone nor the size of the zone. This means that Zone A is protected if it has only one resident and this person’s income is below the poverty line, but an adjacent Zone B with 10 low-income residents and 90 high-income residents will be unprotected if the threshold for classifying a zone as “low-income protected” is greater than 10%. This arbitrary dis- tinction could be interpreted to mean that the one person in Zone A is somehow valued more than the 10 low-income residents in Zone B. If the zonal boundaries change, perhaps neither zone would be pro- tected. Also, the classification of a zone as protected or unprotected may change depending on how the groups are defined. For exam- ple, a racially and ethnically diverse zone may be protected under a “minority” designation but unprotected if separate designations are used for each racial and ethnic class. Use of the geographic unit as a proxy for the group unit does not work well for groups that do not congregate spatially. Although mem- bers of some minority groups may tend to reside in geographic prox- imity to one another, members of other minority groups may be more dispersed. This problem is especially evident when groups such as disabled and elderly populations are considered. Each zone may have an approximately equal percentage of members of a spatially dis- tributed group, making determination of protected and unprotected zones arbitrary. CONCLUSION Three challenges faced by EJ analyses in transportation planning are discussed in this paper. Data needs are identified, definitions and applications of equity are offered, and technical issues associated with the unit of analysis are presented. The increased use of household travel survey data, activity-based models, and microsimulation may alleviate some of the data needs. Before starting an EJ analysis, an MPO must decide what type of equity it is trying to achieve and how it will treat the potentially different needs of its population groups. The choice between group and geographic unit must be made carefully, as each has advantages and pitfalls. As transportation planners explore new types of projects and new sources of funding, equity analyses will become more complex. For example, it is becoming more common for metropolitan planning agencies to devote funding to land use improvements with the goal of reducing automobile use or efficiently using the existing transporta- tion network. The impact of land use improvements, such as transit- oriented development, on various sectors of the population has not yet been studied extensively. The equitable distribution of these projects Duthie, Cervenka, and Waller 11 12 Transportation Research Record 2013 across a region does not ensure equitable impacts, as low-income populations may be “priced out” if gentrification occurs. The increasing popularity of toll roads, managed lanes, and com- prehensive development agreements with private developers poses new challenges for equity analyses. The distinction between public and private goods in transportation has always been blurry, as people must purchase the appropriate equipment (i.e., an automobile, bicy- cle, or shoes) to use most modes of travel and the marginal impact of each person on most systems is not constant (20). MPOs, with the assistance of the public and stakeholders, must make difficult decisions on how to meet the transportation needs of their regions without limiting access and benefits for specific groups. REFERENCES 1. Executive Order 12898. Federal Actions to Address Environmental Justice in Minority Populations and Low-Income Populations. Federal Register, Vol. 59, 1994, p. 7629 (Section 1-101), 3 C.F.R. §859. Reprinted in 42 U.S.C. §4321. 2. Forkenbrock, D. J., and L. A. Schweitzer. Environmental Justice in Transportation Planning. Journal of the American Planning Association, Vol. 65, 1999, pp. 96–111. 3. Chakraborty, J., L. A. Schweitzer, and D. J. Forkenbrock. Using GIS to Assess the Environmental Justice Consequences of Transportation System Changes. Transactions in GIS, Vol. 3, 1999, pp. 239–258. 4. Bullard, R., G. Johnson, and A. Torres. Highway Robbery: Transporta- tion Racism and New Routes to Equity. South End Press, Cambridge, Mass., 2004. 5. Kain, J. F., and J. R. Meyer. Transportation and Poverty. Public Interest, Vol. 18, 1970, pp. 75–87. 6. Collin, R. W., T. Beatley, and W. Harris. Environmental Racism: A Chal- lenge to Community Development. Journal of Black Studies, Vol. 25, No. 3, 1995, pp. 354–376. 7. Lane, L. B., S. Hoffeld, and D. Griffin. Environmental Justice Evalua- tion: Wilmington Bypass, Wilmington, North Carolina. In Transporta- tion Research Record 1626, TRB, National Research Council, Washington, D.C., 1998, pp. 131–139. 8. Hodge, D. C. Fiscal Equity in Urban Mass Transit Systems: A Geographic Analysis. Annals of the Association of American Geographers, Vol. 78, No. 2, 1988, pp. 288–306. 9. Wachs, M. U.S. Transit Subsidy Policy: In Need of Reform. Science, Vol. 244, 1989, pp. 1545–1549. 10. Pucher, J. Who Benefits from Transit Subsidies? Recent Evidence from Six Metropolitan Areas. Transportation Research, Vol. 17A, No. 1, 1983, pp. 39–50. 11. Puentes, R., and R. Prince. Fueling Transportation Finance: A Primer on the Gas Tax. The Brookings Institution, Washington, D.C., March 2003. 12. Taylor, B. The Geography of Urban Transportation Finance. In The Geog- raphy of Urban Transportation, The Guilford Press, New York, 2004. 13. Shahidullah, M., and S. K. Smith. An Evaluation of Population Projection Errors for Census Tracts. Journal of the American Statistical Association, Vol. 90, 1995, pp. 64–71. 14. Hirschman, C. Race and Ethnic Population Projections: A Critical Eval- uation of Their Content and Meaning. Presented at 13th SUNY—Albany Conference on American Diversity: A Demographic Challenge for the Twenty-First Century, Albany, N.Y., 1994. 15. Smith, S. K., and J. M. Nogle. An Evaluation of Hispanic Population Estimates. Social Science Quarterly, Vol. 85, No. 3, 2004, pp. 731–745. 16. Purvis, C. L. Data and Analysis Methods for Metropolitan-Level Environmental Justice Assessment. In Transportation Research Record: Journal of the Transportation Research Board, No. 1756, TRB, National Research Council, Washington, D.C., 2001, pp. 15–21. 17. Cambridge Systematics, Inc. Technical Methods to Support Analysis of Environmental Justice Issues. Final report for NCHRP Project 8-36(11). TRB, National Research Council, Washington, D.C., 2002. 18. Deka, D. Social and Environmental Justice Issues in Urban Trans- portation. In The Geography of Urban Transportation, Guilford Press, New York, 2004. 19. Taylor, B. The Geography of Urban Transportation Finance. In The Geography of Urban Transportation, Guilford Press, New York, 2004. 20. Litman, T. Evaluating Transportation Equity: Guidance for Incorporating Distributional Impacts on Transportation Planning. Victoria Transport Policy Institute, Victoria, British Columbia, Canada, 2006. 21. Khisty, C. J. Operationalizing Concepts of Equity for Public Project Investments. In Transportation Research Record 1559, TRB, National Research Council, Washington, D.C., 1996, pp. 94–99. 22. Lee, D. B. Making the Concept of Equity Operational. In Transportation Research Record 677, TRB, National Research Council, Washington, D.C., 1978, pp. 48–53. 23. Burbank, C. J., and C. Adams. Status of Environmental Justice Activities. Memorandum to FHWA Division Administrators and FTA Regional Administrators, Jan. 19, 2000. 24. The Facts—Questions and Answers on Environmental Justice. FHWA. www.fhwa.dot.gov/environment/ejustice/facts/index.htm#QA. Last modified Jan. 30, 2002. Accessed July 27, 2007. 25. 2003 Annual Report. Denver Regional Council of Governments, Den- ver, Colo., 2003. www.drcog.org/index.cfm?page=2003AnnualReport. Accessed July 30, 2006. 26. Levinson, D. Identifying Winners and Losers in Transportation. In Transportation Research Record: Journal of the Transportation Research Board, No. 1812, Transportation Research Board of the National Academies, Washington, D.C., 2002, pp. 179–185. 27. Connors, R., A. Sumalee, and D. Watling. Equitable Network Design. Journal of the Eastern Asia Society for Transportation Studies, Vol. 6, 2005, pp. 1382–1397. The Environmental Justice in Transportation Committee sponsored publication of this paper. work_dmkrxvsmj5cwji2jmapujqupzu ---- LAW WP 03_2010 DEPARTMENT OF LAW EUI Working Papers LAW 2010/03 DEPARTMENT OF LAW CONSTITUTIONAL JUSTICE AND THE PERENNIAL TASK OF ‘CONSTITUTIONALIZING’ LAW AND SOCIETY THROUGH ‘PARTICIPATORY JUSTICE’ Ernst-Ulrich Petersmann EUROPEAN UNIVERSITY INSTITUTE, FLORENCE DEPARTMENT OF LAW Constitutional Justice and the Perennial Task of ‘Constitutionalizing’ Law and Society through ‘Participatory Justice’ ERNST-ULRICH PETERSMANN EUI Working Paper LAW 2010/03 This text may be downloaded for personal research purposes only. Any additional reproduction for other purposes, whether in hard copy or electronically, requires the consent of the author(s), editor(s). If cited or quoted, reference should be made to the full name of the author(s), editor(s), the title, the working paper or other series, the year, and the publisher. ISSN 1725-6739 © 2010 Ernst-Ulrich Petersmann Printed in Italy European University Institute Badia Fiesolana I – 50014 San Domenico di Fiesole (FI) Italy www.eui.eu cadmus.eui.eu Author contact details Prof. Dr. Ernst-Ulrich Petersmann Professor of International and European Law European University Institute, Florence, Italy. Email: Ulrich.Petersmann@EUI.eu This paper is a contribution to the forthcoming conference book edited by H.Micklitz, The Many Concepts of Social Justice in European Private Law (2010). Abstract This contribution argues that concepts of social justice in European and international private law must remain consistent with the principles of justice underlying European and international public law. The contribution begins with a brief explanation of the diversity of conceptions of constitutional justice and of their legal impact on ever more fields of European public and private law (1). After clarifying the constitutional terminology used in this contribution (2), Rawlsian principles of justice for national and international law (3) are distinguished from multilevel human rights as principles of justice (4), multilevel judicial protection of constitutional rights and rule of law by ‘courts of justice’ (5), and the diverse forms of democratic and private ‘participatory justice’ for transforming legal and social relationships (6). The constitutional dimensions of the 2007 Lisbon Treaty (as discussed in section 7) confirm that the ‘many concepts of social justice in European private law’ - the focus of this conference book - must be construed and developed with due regard to the diverse dimensions of ‘constitutional justice’ in European and international public law. Keywords constitutional law; constitutionalization; distributive justice; ECHR; ECJ; economic law; EU law; human rights; justice; Lisbon Treaty; multilevel constitutionalism; participatory justice; principles of justice; private law; Rawlsian principles of justice; social justice; theories of justice 1 1. Diverse Conceptions of ‘Constitutional Justice’ for Justifying National and International Law The EU Charter of Fundamental Rights, UN human rights instruments and many national constitutions (like Article 1 of the German Basic Law of 1949) proceed from respect for human dignity as source of inalienable human rights that must be protected by rule of law and democratic governance. This modern constitutional foundation of national and international legal systems can be interpreted in conformity with Immanuel Kant’s moral theory of human rights: Respect for the moral, rational and reasonable autonomy (dignity) of human beings justifies individual rights to equal external freedoms and corresponding moral duties to protect equal freedoms in all human interactions at national, transnational and international levels through multilevel constitutional guarantees.1 As ‘(e)ach person possesses an inviolability founded on justice that even the welfare of society as a whole cannot override’, justice is – as famously proclaimed by J.Rawls – ‘the first virtue of social institutions, as truth is of systems of thought’.2 The term ‘constitutional justice’ can be used broadly in this Rawlsian sense as referring to constitutional ‘principles of justice’ and institutions (like ‘courts of justice’) for the moral and legal assessment of post-constitutional legislation, administration, adjudication and private conduct structuring social relations among free and equal citizens. The diverse procedural, conventional, egalitarian, redistributive, corrective, commutative and social principles of justice can be conceived as sub-categories within this broader concept of ‘constitutional justice.’ The moral assessment of individual and collective actions within the basic structure of rules is the domain of ethics and justice as a virtue of personal conduct. Principles of constitutional justice for designing and improving a just national and international order remain dependent on moral analysis of such social conduct (e.g. the individual responsibility of citizens to participate in designing and maintaining their society’s institutional order) and of the ‘circumstances of justice’ (e.g. the rational egoism and limited reasonableness of individuals constrained by scarcity of resources in their pursuit of a good life) that make just rules and institutions necessary for a stable social order protecting peaceful cooperation among free and equal citizens with often diverse conceptions for a good life and for social justice. The main proposition of this contribution is that principles of ‘constitutional justice’ are of fundamental importance for the legitimacy and stability of social order and may also influence judicial interpretation and legislative harmonization of private law. Sections 3 to 6 briefly summarize four different, yet complementary conceptions of ‘constitutional justice’: Justice as constitutional fairness (3); justice as multilevel constitutional guarantees of human rights and protection of basic human needs (4); constitutional justice as multilevel judicial protection of individual rights and ‘rule of law’ in conformity with ‘principles of justice’ in relations among individuals, among individuals and governments, as well as among states (5); as well as democratic and private forms of ‘participatory justice’ for agreed transformations of social relations (6). Human rights and constitutional law make ‘constitutionalizing’ law and social cooperation across Europe a perennial task of democratic lawmakers, governments, ‘courts of justice’ and of civil society. The judgment by the German Constitutional Court in the famous Lüth case (concerning a private boycott against a film produced by a former Nazi film director) of 1958 – in which the Court inferred from Article 1(3) of the German Basic Law that fundamental constitutional rights (such as the general personality right and freedom of expression protected by Articles 2 and 5 of the Basic Law), apart from granting individual rights, also prescribe objective constitutional values that apply to the whole legal order and must be taken into 1 On the diverse interpretations of Kant’s moral, historical and political conceptions of natural rights see, e.g.: G.Beck, Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Rights, Ratio Juris 19 (2006), 371-401. 2 J.Rawls (rev. edition 1999), at 3. Ernst-Ulrich Petersmann 2 account in judicial interpretation of general private law clauses3 - illustrates the potential relevance of constitutional law for the interpretation and judicial protection of private law, as recognized also in the case-law of the European Court of Justice (e.g. the 2007 ECJ judgments in the Laval and Viking cases) and in the Preamble to the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union: ‘Enjoyment of these rights entails responsibilities and duties with regard to other persons, to the human community and to future generations.’4 The relevance of European constitutional law for influencing, justifying or limiting harmonization and ‘constitutionalization’ of private law in Europe remains, however, contested. As European constitutional law is committed to ‘respecting the diversity of the cultures and traditions of the peoples of Europe as well as the national identities of the Member States and the organization of their public authorities at national, regional and local levels’ (Preamble to the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights), the constitutional principles of EU law may also be invoked for justifying the prevailing diversity of national private law systems in EU member states. 2. Defining ‘Constitutions’, ‘Constitutionalism’ and ‘Constitutionalization’ The terms ‘constitution’, constitutionalism’ and ‘constitutionalization’ are used in this contribution in the following ways:  Constitution refers to a coherent set of long-term principles and rules of a higher legal rank constituting the basic order of a political community (e.g. in a state), or of a functionally limited community (e.g. based on an international ‘treaty constitution’ for the collective supply of international public goods), with legislative, administrative and dispute settlement functions for the maintenance of rule of law for the benefit of citizens. Many national rules (e.g. ‘basic laws’, charters of human rights) and international ‘treaty constitutions’ can serve ‘constitutional functions’ for protecting equal rights, rule of law and transparent self-governance of citizens in public and private law relations even if the respective rules are not formally designated as ‘constitutional.’  Constitutionalism refers to the political method of using constitutional principles, rules and institutions (such as constitutional conventions elaborating constitutional rules) for the collective supply of national and international public goods that benefit all citizens concerned. Multilevel constitutionalism uses constitutional principles, rules and institutions at national and international levels of governance (e.g. legal organizations constituting legislative, executive and judicial powers protecting rule of law among citizens) for the collective supply of international public goods.  Constitutionalization refers to legal methods aimed at strengthening constitutional principles, rules and institutions (like independent judicial protection of constitutional rights and ‘constitutional justice’) in the diverse forms of national and international rule-making, rule-administration and rule-enforcement. Due to the independence and impartiality of ‘courts of justice’ (e.g. compared with majoritarian political institutions) and their judicial ‘administration of justice’ on the basis of ‘due process of law’, judicial settlement – at national and international levels - of disputes over the interpretation and application of rules, and the resulting clarification and continuous adaptation of legal systems to the needs of citizens, offer a distinct mode of ‘multilevel judicial governance’ and principle-oriented ‘constitutional restraint’ on political rule-making and policy-making. As many international disputes are, directly or indirectly (e.g. by means of ‘diplomatic protection’ of individual rights by the home state), initiated at the request of citizens in order to defend their 3 BVerfGE 7, 198 (15 January 1958); cf. H.Rösler, Harmonizing the German Civil Code of the 19th Century with a Modern Constitution – The Lüth Revolution 50 years ago in Comparative Perspective, in: Tulane European and Civil Law Forum 23 (2008), 1 ff. 4 Cf. O.J. EU C 306 of 17 December 2007 and: The Lisbon Treaty. The Readable Version (Foundation for EU Democracy 2008), at 199. Constitutional Justice and the Perennial Task of ‘Constitutionalizing’ Law and Society through ‘Participatory Justice’ 3 rights against alleged abuses of private and public power, ‘judicial governance’ complements the diverse modes of self-governance of citizens in constitutional democracies as well as in the multilevel governance of international cooperation among citizens.5 3. How to Interpret the EU Law Commitments to ‘Justice’? Rawlsian ‘Justice as Constitutional Fairness’ in National and International Law-Making All EU member states have adopted national constitutions based on the insight of democratic constitutionalism that a society’s legal and institutional order may be justified, improved and politically supported over time by constitutional agreement on political ‘principles of justice’ of a higher legal rank (e.g. for constituting, designing and limiting rights of citizens, human rights and democratic governance institutions) that must respect and protect the legitimate diversity of moral, religious and political conceptions of citizens and can be freely supported by all reasonable citizens.6 Such an ‘overlapping consensus’ on a limited ‘political conception of justice’ can help justifying, maintaining and adapting a stable social order, endorsed by citizens with competing worldviews, if the principles respect and protect basic human needs and remain compatible with the enduring reality of diverse, and partially conflicting, moral, religious and other worldviews of citizens. Also in European law and integration, a shared conception of ‘principles of political justice’ justifying the ‘basic structure’ of European rules and institutions – as agreed in the 2007 Lisbon Treaty as well as in the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights which, inter alia, codify principles and rules of European constitutional law - can help resolve disputes on how constitutional rules and individual rights are to be developed over time and adapted to changing circumstances. The Treaty on European Union (as amended by the Lisbon Treaty), like the new Treaty on the Functioning of the EU and the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights as integral part of EU law, include numerous provisions referring to ‘justice’ (e.g. Article 2 TEU), for instance regarding the EU’s ‘area of freedom, security and justice’ (e.g. Article 3 TEU, Arts. 67 ff TFEU), the ‘Court of Justice of the EU’ (Arts. 251 ff TFEU) and fundamental rights to justice (Title VI of the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights). Such explicit references of EU law to justice reflect the longstanding European tradition, since ancient Greek law, of conceptualizing law as participation in the idea of justice. Rawls’ Theory of Justice aims at promoting an ‘overlapping consensus’ among citizens on (1) a common moral justification of (2) principles of political justice for (3) the design, and adjustment over time, of the ‘basic structure’ of a stable social order. In accordance with this tripartite objective, Rawls conceived his Theory of Justice as having three tiers: the ‘original position’ on the top level is a contractualist thought experiment necessary for ensuring ‘justice as fairness’ in the social agreement, on the middle level, on two principles of justice7 (with two priority rules) that constitutionally guide and restrain, on the bottom tier, the ‘basic structure’ of rules concretizing and institutionalizing the ‘principles of justice’ so as to sustain a stable order for social cooperation among citizens with fundamental interests in a good life, in a shared public conception of justice, and in successfully pursuing their chosen life plans. As citizens are not only shaped and bound by, but also collectively 5 Cf. Joerges/Petersmann, (2006). See also M.Shapiro/A.Stone Sweet (2004), chapter 4 (describing adjudication as a particular mode of governance, through which the legal structures of a legal community are continuously adapted to the needs and purposes of citizens and governments). 6 On this ‘idea of a well-ordered society’ respecting the ‘fact of reasonable pluralism’ and pursuing only a limited conception of ‘political justice’ see: J.Rawls (1993), at 35 ff. 7 Rawls’ first statement of the two principles reads as follows: ‘First: each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive scheme of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar scheme of liberties for others. Second: social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are both (a) reasonable expected to be to everyone’s advantage, and (b) attached to positions and offices open to all’ (Rawls, rev. ed. 1999, at 53). Ernst-Ulrich Petersmann 4 responsible for their social order, the Rawlsian constitutional theory justifies constitutional rules as resulting from justice as fairness, and as being in the rational self-interest of all reasonable citizens affected by the rules. In order to protect the ‘constitutional contract’ from being distorted by differential bargaining power and potential threats favouring certain contracting parties, the reasoning of citizens and balancing of their diverse interests must take place behind a ‘veil of ignorance’ (Rawls) ensuring equal consideration for all citizens. As, in such an ‘original position’, all individual interests are represented fairly and the constitutional principles of justice protect equal access of citizens to the ‘social primary goods’ essential for their individual well-being (e.g. equal basic liberties, rights and opportunities)8, ‘justice as fairness’ (Rawls) suggests that also the principles of justice and basic rules and institutions justified by such a ‘constitutional contract’ are to be accepted as fair and just by all individuals living under this social order. European constitutional law reflects Rawlsian principles of justice and of procedural fairness in diverse, albeit imperfect ways. For instance, similar to the features of Rawls’ ‘original position’ for negotiating national and international principles of justice (such as the ‘veil of ignorance’, the requirement of publicity and unanimity, the negotiation of international principles of justice by representatives of national peoples rather than by individuals), the elaboration of the Lisbon Treaty and of the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights (as entered into force on 1 December 2009) by intergovernmental negotiations and ‘European Conventions’ (which elaborated the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights adopted on 8 December 2000 as well as the 2003 Draft Constitution for Europe9), and the ratification of the Lisbon Treaty by national parliaments, the European Parliament and by popular referenda, offered uniquely comprehensive procedures for taking into account interests of all groups of European societies and of their democratically elected representatives. EU law includes much broader and more detailed, constitutional as well as judicial guarantees of transnational liberty rights, equality rights, solidarity rights, citizen rights and rights of ‘access to justice’ (e.g. in terms of national and European judicial remedies) than any national constitution of any of the 192 UN member states. In spite of the economic origins of European law (e.g. in the European Atomic, Coal and Steel as well as Economic Communities), justice has become recognized – in line with the Rawlsian theory of justice – as being prior to utilitarian promotion of economic welfare through market integration and sectoral policy integration. Also the controversial, eight Rawlsian principles for an international ‘law of peoples’10 – respect for the freedom and independence of people, pacta sund servanda, equality of people, non-intervention, the right of self-defense, respect for human rights, for the laws of war and international development assistance – are all reflected in corresponding EU law principles. Likewise, the Rawlsian explanation of the causes of economic welfare in terms of domestic legal and political culture11 seems to be confirmed by the relative welfare in each EU member state, just as Rawls’ support for the longstanding ‘democratic peace argument’ (i.e. the explanation by philosophers like Montesquieu, Kant and A.Smith that voluntary international trade contributes to peaceful cooperation across frontiers among democracies)12 appears to be confirmed by the ‘democratic peace’ among all 27 EU member states. 8 Cf. Rawls (rev. ed. 1999), at 52 ff, 78 ff; on the lexical priority of basic liberties (which may be reduced only for the sake of basic liberties but not for the sake of any other social primary goods), see 36 ff. 9 Cf. J.M.Beneyto, From Nice to the Constitutional Treaty. Eight Theses on the (Future) Constitutionalisation of Europe, in: Griller/J.Ziller (2008), at 1-20. 10 J.Rawls (1999), at 36-37. 11 Rawls (1999), at 108 ff. 12 Cf. Rawls (1999), at 51-54. Constitutional Justice and the Perennial Task of ‘Constitutionalizing’ Law and Society through ‘Participatory Justice’ 5 4. Justice as Multilevel Constitutional Guarantees of Human Rights The multilevel, constitutional protection of human rights through national laws, European law and international human rights conventions in all EU member states reflects Kant’s theory of justice based on multilevel constitutional guarantees of human rights to maximum equal freedoms. In contrast to the US tradition of prioritizing civil and political liberties over economic and social rights ensuring fulfilment of basic socio-economic needs, Rawls later recognized that ‘the first principle covering the equal basic rights and liberties may easily be preceded by a lexically prior principle requiring that citizens’ basic socio-economic needs be met, at least insofar as their being met is necessary for citizens to understand and to be able fruitfully to exercise those rights and liberties.’ 13 This Rawlsian acknowledgement - that fulfilment of basic needs may be among the ‘equal basic rights and liberties of citizenship’14 – corresponds to the today worldwide recognition, in hundreds of national and international human rights instruments, of ‘inalienable’ and ‘indivisible’ civil, political, economic, social and cultural human rights to be respected and protected by national and international legal systems.15 By explicitly acknowledging (e.g. in the Preambles of the European Convention on Human Rights and of the 1966 UN Covenants on civil, political, economic, social and cultural human rights) ‘the equal and inalienable rights of all members of the human family (as) the foundation of freedom, justice and peace in the world’, human rights are simultaneously recognized as ‘principles of justice’ limiting governance powers and guiding legislation, administration and adjudication. European Community law and the 2007 Treaty of Lisbon provide for comprehensive constitutional rights, human rights and other ‘principles of justice’ for an ‘area of freedom, security and justice without internal frontiers’ (Article 2 TEU), safeguarded by multilevel legal and judicial remedies in national and European courts. The EU Charter of Fundamental Rights emphasizes that ‘the Union is founded on the indivisible, universal values of human dignity, freedom, equality and solidarity; it is based on the principles of democracy and the rule of law. It places the individual at the heart of its activities, by establishing the citizenship of the Union and by creating an area of freedom, security and justice’ (Preamble). 16 The comprehensive legal guarantees of the EU Charter for the protection of dignity rights, liberty rights, equality rights, solidarity rights, citizen rights and judicial rights, like the Lisbon Treaty’s requirement of EU accession to the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms (ECHR), reflect a dynamic evolution, and slow convergence, of national and international human rights and constitutional rights in Europe limiting multilevel governance and protecting social justice beyond national frontiers. The recognition of a human right to respect for, and protection of, human dignity by national and European courts, notwithstanding its diverse judicial interpretation within particular jurisdictions17, has promoted judicial protection also of basic human needs for a decent life and work in dignity (e.g. offering special protection to weaker parties like 13 Rawls (1993), at 7. Rawls specifies (at 166) that the level of well-being and education required depends on the level of development of the respective society; someone’s basic socio-economic needs are met if she has the requisite means (including education) to take part in the social and political life of the society as a citizen. 14 Cf. Rawls (1993), at 227 ff. 15 E.U.Petersmann, Human Rights, Markets and Economic Welfare: Constitutional Functions of the Emerging UN Human Rights Constitution, in: F.Abbott/C.Breining/T.Cottier (2006), 29-67. 16 Cf. The Lisbon Treaty (note 4), at 198. 17 Cf. C.McCrudden, Human Dignity and Judicial Interpretation of Human Rights, in: 19 EJIL (2008), 655 ff. Ernst-Ulrich Petersmann 6 foreign workers, refugees, migrants and their families inside EC member states).18 The new Article 6 TEU on the legally binding effect of the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights, on EU accession to the ECHR, and on fundamental rights as ‘general principles of the Union’s law’ will further strengthen the multilevel constitutional character of European law and its constitutional safeguards of fundamental rights and ‘principles of justice’ constraining multilevel governance inside the EU.19 5. Justice through Multilevel Judicial Protection of Constitutional Rights and Rule of Law As an alternative to Rawls’ ‘original position’ as the basis for ‘justice as fairness’, the ethical theory of T.Scanlon20 and the theory of justice by B.Barry21 posit participants who are aware of their identities and motivated to seek agreement under conditions of impartiality and terms that nobody could reasonably reject. The constitutional protection of human rights of access to justice (e.g. in the sense of individual access to legal and judicial remedies, cf. Articles 6, 13 ECHR) and of independent courts administering justice impartially, subject to ‘due process of law’, are examples of constitutional justice as multilevel judicial protection of fundamental rights and ‘rule of law’ as constitutional restraints on ‘rule by men’ and their ‘rule by law.’22 The functional interrelationships between law, judges and justice are reflected in legal language from antiquity (e.g. in the common core of the Latin terms jus, judex, justitia) up to modern times (cf. the Anglo-American legal traditions of speaking of courts of justice, and giving judges the title of Mr. Justice, Lord Justice, or Chief Justice). Like the Roman god Janus, justice and judges face two different perspectives: Their ‘conservative function’ is to apply the existing law and protect the existing system of rights so as ‘to render to each person what is his [right].’ Yet, laws tend to be incomplete and subject to change. Hence, impartial justice may require ‘reformative interpretations’ of legal rules in response to changing social conceptions of justice. As explained by R.Dworkin, courts of justice should interpret law in conformity with its rule-of-law objectives and its underlying principles of justice.23 Dworkin’s ‘adjudicative principle of integrity’ requires judges to interpret law as expressing ‘a coherent conception of justice and fairness’: 18 On ‘capabilities approaches’ to the interpretation of human rights (as developed by A.Sen and M.C.Nussbaum) see: M.C.Nussbaum (2006). 19 On protection of citizen rights by means of the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights see: I.Pernice, The Treaty of Lisbon and Fundamental Rights, in: Griller/Ziller (2008), at 235 ff. 20 T.Scanlon (1998). 21 B.M.Barry (1995). 22 On the dialectic developments of constitutional rights and principles of justice restraining the instrumental ‘governance by law’ see already Aristotle, The Politics and the Constitution of Athens (1996), book III, para.16, at 1287 a-b. On ‘rule of men’ as domination, and ‘rule of law’ as non-domination, see: P.Pettit (1997). According to F.A.Hayek (1960), it is ‘because the lawgiver does not know the particular cases to which his rules will apply, and it is because the judge who applies them has no choice in drawing the conclusions that follow from the existing body of rules and the particular facts of the case, that it can be said that laws and not men rule’ (at 153). Rule of law differs from ‘rule by law’ and ‘rule by men’ in terms of constitutional safeguards such as judicial enforcement of law vis-à-vis private persons and public authorities and judicial protection of human rights and other principles of justice. Yet, the historical division between common law and equity law in England (where the Court of Chancery provided additional remedies in certain situations if the common law courts failed to do so) illustrates the long-standing claim by theories of justice (e.g. Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 1999, at 1137b-1138a) that equitable and reasonable interpretation and application of the law may require judges to address particular circumstances of the dispute justifying particular interpretations of ‘principles of justice’, ‘rules of reason’ and ‘rules of recognition’ in order to do justice to particular circumstances of disputes. 23 R.Dworkin (2006), at 9-21. Constitutional Justice and the Perennial Task of ‘Constitutionalizing’ Law and Society through ‘Participatory Justice’ 7 ‘Law as integrity asks judges to assume, so far as this is possible, that the law is structured by a coherent set of principles about justice and fairness and procedural due process, and it asks them to enforce these in the fresh cases that come before them, so that each person’s situation is fair and just according to the same standards.’ 24 The European Court of Justice, for example, protects the fundamental rights and human rights of 500 million EU citizens not only vis-à-vis restrictions by EU institutions and by member states, but also against abuses of power in the ‘horizontal relations’ among citizens (e.g. in labour markets and consumer markets).25 The ever more comprehensive jurisdictions and judicial remedies inside constitutional democracies and in European courts confirm the Kantian postulate that ‘perpetual peace’ – both inside nations as well as across nations - requires constitutional rights and judicial protection of ‘rule of law’ in all social interactions of citizens, i.e. among individuals, among individuals and governments, as well as among states.26 The development of the customary international law rules for the protection of aliens, which require states to provide decent justice to foreigners and ‘to create and maintain a system of justice which ensures that unfairness to foreigners either does not happen, or is corrected’27, into human rights of access to justice28 illustrates the progressive transformation of state-centred into citizen-oriented rules also in international law. The ever larger number of international treaties, notably in the field of international economic and environmental law, providing for individual rights of access to courts confronts judges with a ‘constitutional dilemma’:  On the one side, citizens increasingly invoke specific treaty rules (e.g. relating to human rights, labour rights, intellectual property rights, investor rights, trading rights, fishing rights, protection of the environment) in national and international courts.  On the other side, most intergovernmental treaties do not offer effective individual legal and judicial remedies29; hence, national, European and international judges are increasingly confronted with legal claims that intergovernmental treaty rules on the protection of individual rights - e.g. in UN human rights conventions, conventions on intellectual property rights adopted in the context of the of the World Intellectual Property Organization, in conventions on labour and social rights adopted in the context of the International Labour Organization, rules of the World Trade Organization, regional trade agreements on individual freedoms of trade and in investment treaties protecting investor rights - should be legally protected by judges as justifying not only rights of governments, but also individual rights and legal remedies against arbitrary violations by governments of their international treaty obligations to the detriment of domestic citizens. 24 R.Dworkin (1986), at 225, 243. 25 Cf. B. De Witte, Balancing of Economic Law and Human Rights by the European Court of Justice, in: Dupuy/Francioni/Petersmann (2009), 197-207. 26 Cf. I.Kant, Perpetual Peace, in: Kant Political Writings (1991), at 98 f. 27 J.Paulsson (2006), at 7, 36. 28 Cf. F.Francioni (2007). 29 Cf. J.Dugard, First Report on Diplomatic Protection (International Law Commission UN Doc. A/CN.4/506, 2000), para. 25: ‘To suggest that universal human rights conventions, particularly the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, provide individuals with effective remedies for the protection of their human rights is to engage in a fantasy which, unlike fiction, has no place in legal reasoning. The sad truth is that only a handful of individuals, in the limited number of States that accept the right to individual petition to the monitoring bodies of these conventions, have obtained or will obtain satisfactory remedies from these conventions.’ Ernst-Ulrich Petersmann 8 According to Rawls, ‘in a constitutional regime with judicial review, public reason is the reason of its supreme court’; it is of constitutional importance for the ‘overlapping, constitutional consensus’ necessary for a stable and just society among free, equal and rational citizens who tend to be deeply divided by conflicting moral, religious and philosophical doctrines.30 Also in international law, the UN Charter (Article 1) and the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties (VCLT) recall the general obligation under international law ‘that disputes concerning treaties, like other international disputes, should be settled by peaceful means and in conformity with the principles of justice and international law’, including ‘universal respect for, and observance of, human rights and fundamental freedoms for all’ (VCLT, Preamble). The ECJ, the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR) and the European Free Trade Area (EFTA) Court successfully transformed the intergovernmental European Community (EC) treaties and the ECHR into constitutional orders founded on respect for human rights.31 Their ‘judicial constitutionalization’ of intergovernmental treaty regimes was accepted by citizens, national courts, parliaments and governments because the judicial ‘European public reason’ protected more effectively individual rights and European ‘public goods’ (like the EC’s common market). The ‘Solange method’ of cooperation among European courts ‘as long as’ constitutional rights are adequately protected, reflects an ‘overlapping constitutional consensus’ on the need for ‘constitutional justice’ and judicial cooperation (comity) in the multilevel judicial protection of rule of law in European integration. 6. Progressive ‘Constitutionalization’ of Legal and Social Relationships through Participatory Justice with Due Regard for ‘Reasonable Disagreement’ The legitimate diversity of national democratic constitutions illustrates that the transformation of ‘principles of justice’ into constitutional, legislative, administrative and judicial rules and institutions may legitimately vary among constitutional democracies according to their democratic preferences and historical experiences. The diversity of national and international human rights instruments and related constitutional guarantees likewise confirms that the two Rawlsian principles of justice – maximum equal liberties and a ‘difference principle’ protecting the least advantaged in societies – can be specified by very diverse civil, political, economic, social and cultural liberty rights and corresponding governance obligations depending, inter alia, on the respective constitutional traditions, democratic preferences and economic resources of the people concerned. For example, while multilevel cooperation among national and international courts in Europe in their clarification and judicial protection of international guarantees of freedom (e.g. in the EC Treaty, the EEA Agreement, the ECHR) have promoted a progressive ‘constitutionalization’ of ‘international law among sovereign states’ for the benefit of constitutional rights of European citizens, judicial cooperation among international and national courts outside Europe protecting individual rights remains limited to a few areas such as international criminal law (where national and international criminal courts increasingly cooperate in protecting victims’ rights), international investment law (where national courts recognize and enforce transnational investor-state arbitral awards), regional economic and human rights law (e.g. in a few regional human rights courts and regional free trade areas with regional economic courts as in the Andean Common Market and MERCOSUR ). Participation and legal protection of citizens are the legitimizing factors in the elaboration of Rawlsian principles of justice, in judicial protection of human rights as well as in democratic legislation transforming general principles of justice and human rights into specific rules and institutions for peaceful cooperation among citizens. The pervasive reality of conflicts of interests among individuals competing for scarce resources, like the often unconscious conflicts inside the human mind (e.g. among rational egoism, limited reasonableness, emotional passions and unconscious instincts of 30 J.Rawls (1993), at 231 ff. 31 Cf. E.U.Petersmann, Human Rights, International Economic Law and ‘Constitutional Justice’, EJIL 19 (2008) 769-798. Constitutional Justice and the Perennial Task of ‘Constitutionalizing’ Law and Society through ‘Participatory Justice’ 9 individuals), require dispute prevention and dispute resolution through ‘pre-commitment’ to constitutional rules and dispute resolution procedures not only in ‘political markets’ (e.g. so as to protect citizens against abuses of government powers), but also in private markets (e.g. so as to protect employees in labour markets and consumers in economic markets against abuses of private economic power and ‘information asymmetries’). Political markets, labour markets and economic markets for private goods and services reveal similar ‘market failures’ that must be constitutionally restrained by constitutional rules of a higher legal rank (e.g. for protecting equal freedoms and non-discriminatory competition) as well as by ‘participatory justice institutions’ (e.g. for parliamentary and judicial protection of citizen-driven ‘deliberative democracy’, consumer-driven market competition and ‘freedom of commercial speech’). The increasing calls for ‘transforming social relationships through participatory justice’ - beyond ‘deliberative democracy’, participatory democratic self-governance and adversarial judicial procedures - reflect the perennial task of progressively ‘constitutionalizing’ public and private law systems in order to prevent and resolve social conflicts (e.g. by promoting public and private ‘mediation’ procedures reflecting constitutional values like rule of law, dialogue among the disputants and voluntarily agreed dispute settlements aimed at ‘consensus-based justice’).32 Conflicts of interests are not only enduring features of all societies; rules and procedures for peaceful conflict resolution based on ‘participatory justice’ also offer opportunities for continuously reviewing, adapting and developing rules, institutions and ‘justice systems’ in response to citizens calling for ever more comprehensive guarantees of ‘social justice’. 7. The Future of European Constitutional Law and ‘Social Justice’ Following the rejection (in popular referenda in France and the Netherlands) of the 2004 Treaty establishing a Constitution for Europe, the 2007 Lisbon Treaty on the European Union was presented as an international treaty without ‘constitutional character’. Yet, – both in terms of a formal, positivist concept of constitution (e.g. as referring to the long-term, basic rules of a higher legal rank constituting the governance system for a political community) as well as in terms of a substantive concept of democratic constitutionalism (e.g. as referring to constitutional citizen rights and basic rules constituting legislative, executive and judicial self-governance) – the Lisbon Treaty codifies and further develops European constitutional rules as they had been acknowledged already in the 2001 Nice Treaty on the EU (e.g. Article 6) and are now being further developed in the TEU (e.g. its Title I) as amended by the Lisbon Treaty. The diverse constitutional structures of the ECHR, of EU law and of EEA law (as interpreted by its EFTA Court) illustrate the legitimately diverse forms of multilevel ‘constitutional pluralism’ in European integration. As long as the European courts continue their successful cooperation with national courts, their multilevel judicial interpretation and protection of the ECHR, of the EU Treaty and EEA agreement as ‘constitutional instruments’ will continue to constitutionally limit private and public legal practices; it seems inconceivable today that the EU courts, the EFTA Court and the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR) could ever abandon their constitutional commitment to judicial protection of fundamental rights protected by EU law, EEA law and the ECHR.33 The case-law of the European courts on ‘horizontal protection’ of fundamental rights also in private relations among citizens in economic and labour markets, like the explicit recognition (e.g. in the Preamble to the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights) that European fundamental rights ‘entail responsibilities and duties with regard to other persons, to the human community and to future generations’, confirm that the ‘principles of justice’ and constitutional restraints of European law limit also private law systems and private legal practices (e.g. in commercial, corporate and competition law, consumer law, labour law, contract law, family law) across EU member states. Without such 32 Cf. Transforming Relationships through Participatory Justice (Law Commission of Canada: Ottawa 2003). 33 On the perennial ‘constitutional problems’ of European integration law see: E.U.Petersmann, The Reform Treaty and the Constitutional Finality of European Integration, in: Griller/Ziller (2009), at 337-358. Ernst-Ulrich Petersmann 10 safeguards of ‘constitutional justice’ and of ‘participatory justice’, the power asymmetries, information asymmetries and other ‘market failures’ in political markets, economic markets and labour markets would risk undermining the European ideals of citizen-driven democratic self- governance, consumer-driven market competition and collective bargaining among employers and employees. The reality of moral, religious, political and legal pluralism, and the need for constitutional legitimacy of European governance on behalf of 500 million European citizens living in 27 nation states, is even more obvious in transnational European integration than inside nation states; both require respect for reasonable, political disagreement and for the social reality of ‘pluralism’ (as explicitly recognized in Article 2 TEU), which often reflects moral disagreement and legitimately diverse social and legal traditions. The Rawlsian theory of justice emphasizes that - in view of the ‘fact of reasonable pluralism’ and ‘the fact that in a democratic regime political power is regarded as the power of free and equal citizens as a collective body’- the democratic exercise of coercive power over one another is democratically legitimate only when ‘political power … is exercised in accordance with a constitution (written or unwritten) the essentials of which all citizens, as reasonable and rational, can endorse in the light of their common human reason.’34 The judicial activism of the European Court of Justice in protecting non-discrimination and social integration of EU citizens exercising their EU market freedoms and claiming access to universal services, like the ECJ judgments (e.g. in the Viking and Laval cases) about the need for reconciling (‘balancing’) the EC ‘market freedoms’ with the rights of trade unions, illustrate that - in disputes over social justice - the exercise of judicial power and judicial reasoning must be justified with due regard to agreed ‘principles of justice’, such as the Lisbon Treaty’s new commitment to a ‘highly competitive social market economy’ (Article 3 TEU) or the ‘dignity rights’ protected in Title I of the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights (which might justify interpreting ‘common market freedoms’ and the ‘liberty rights’ protected in Title II of the Charter in terms of autonomy-based ‘positive liberties’).35 The Lisbon Treaty’s emphasis on, inter alia, the constitutional principles of respect for societal ‘pluralism’ (Article 2 TEU), limited conferral of powers, subsidiarity and proportionality (cf. Article 5 TEU) suggests that EU law may continue to have only a limited impact on private law systems (e.g. for promoting ‘contractual justice’ by means of legal protection of weak parties in contract law, consumer law, labour law and tenancy law). Even if EC legal acts (e.g. EC Directives on harmonization of certain areas of private law like corporate social responsibility) and court decisions are legally binding on their respective addressees, they may be questioned by citizens and political parties if their constitutional legitimacy is not justified in terms of protecting essential interests of EU citizens. Hence, in their judicial interpretation of EU rules and their systemic interrelationships (e.g. between European and national competition laws, labour laws and private law rules), judges must respect legitimately diverse traditions of interpreting and applying ‘principles of justice’ in domestic laws (such as conventional justice in the sense of rule-following, egalitarian justice in the sense of treating like cases alike, distributive justice in conformity with basic needs justifying limited redistribution of income, retributive justice in the sense of just compensation or punishment, reciprocal justice in the sense of mutual advantage, procedural justice and individual justice as protected by human rights). In ‘vertical disputes’ among citizens and governments (such as investment disputes in national courts and investor-state arbitration inside the EU), the legitimate functions of courts, their judicial ‘balancing’ of relevant ‘principles of justice’, and the limits imposed by constitutional rights and competing jurisdictions may differ from those in ‘horizontal disputes’ among governments (e.g. in the ECJ) or in private commercial arbitration. Just as European integration law protects European citizens against harmful border discrimination by national governments, so can legal EU 34 J.Rawls (2001), at 41. 35 On competing constitutional conceptions of liberty rights see, e.g.: K.Möller, Two Conceptions of Positive Liberty: Towards an Autonomy-based Theory of Constitutional Rights, in: Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 29 (2009), 757-786. Constitutional Justice and the Perennial Task of ‘Constitutionalizing’ Law and Society through ‘Participatory Justice’ 11 harmonization of national social and private rules help overcome harmful biases in national social and private law systems (e.g. exclusionary trade union practices preventing competition by posted workers from new EU member states as in the Laval and Viking disputes in the ECJ). Whether, to what extent and in which areas European integration requires, or justifies, harmonization of private law systems remains contested and needs to be legally and judicially clarified with due regard to the ‘principles of justice’ and limited scope of European constitutional law. Ernst-Ulrich Petersmann 12 BIBLIOGRAPHY F.Abbott/C.Breining/T.Cottier (eds), International Trade and Human Rights (OUP: Oxford 2006) Aristotle, The Politics and the Constitution of Athens (ed. by S.Everson, CUP:Cambridge, 1996) Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, ed. by M.Ostwald, Prentice Hall: Upper Sadle River, 1999 B.M.Barry, Justice as Impartiality (Vol. II of A Treatise on Social Justice, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995). P.M.Dupuy/F.Francioni/E.U.Petersmann (eds), Human Rights in International Investment Law and Arbitration (OUP: Oxford, 2009) R.Dworkin, Law’s Empire (Harvard University Press: Cambridge Mass., 1986) R.Dworkin, Justice in Robes (Harvard University Press: Cambridge Mass., 2006) C.Joerges/E.U.Petersmann (eds), Constitutionalism, Multilevel Trade Governance and Social Regulation (Hart Publishers: Oxford, 2006) F.Francioni (ed), Access to Justice as a Human Right (OUP: Oxford, 2007) S.Griller/J.Ziller (eds), The Lisbon Treaty. EU Constitutionalism without a Constitutional Treaty? (Springer Verlag: Vienna, 2008) F.A.Hayek, The Constitution of Liberty (Routledge: London, 1960) Kant Political Writings (ed. by H.Reiss, CUP: Cambridge, 1991) M.C.Nussbaum, Frontiers of Justice (Harvard University Press: Cambridge Mass., 2006) J.Paulsson, Denial of Justice in International Law (OUP: Oxford, 2006) P.Pettit, Republicanism: A Theory of Freedom and Government (1997) M.Shapiro/A.Stone Sweet, On Law, Politics and Judicialization (OUP: Oxford, 2004) J.Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, rev. edition 1999) J.Rawls, Political Liberalism (Columbia University Press: New York, 1993) J.Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Harvard University Press: Cambridge 1999) J.Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement (ed. by E.Kelly; Harvard University Press: Cambridge Mass., 2001) T.Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (Harvard University Press: Cambridge Mass., 1998). work_dnrabiohxzfdplz7f3zdky3kca ---- When Caring Is Just and Justice Is Caring: Justice and Mental Retardation Eva Feder Kittay , “Praise to you, Lord God, king of the universe, who varies the forms of thy creatures.” So begins an ancient Hebrew prayer which is to be recited upon encountering an individual with “deformities.” Wolf Wolfensberger, The Principles of Normalization in Human Services When speaking of a person labeled “profoundly mentally retarded” emphasize “profound.” David Hingsburger, First Contact: Charting Inner Space Interjecting Voice P mong the various human forms alluded to in the Hebrew prayer, mental retardation appears to be one of the most difficult to celebrate.1 It is the disability that other disabled persons do not want attributed to them. It is the dis- ability for which prospective parents are most likely to use selective abortion (Wertz 2000). And it is the disability that prompted one of the most illustrious United States Supreme Court Justices to endorse forced sterilization, because 1. A word about the term mental retard&m. In speaking of mental retardation. some speak of mental disabilities, or cognitive or intellectual disabilities, or developmental disabilities, or being men- tally challenged. 1 reject the last term as condescending. Although only mental retardation captures precisely the population I address, I vary the terms with a sensitivity to their over- or underinclusive- ness. Public Culture 13(3): 557-579 Copyright 0 2001 by Eva Feder Kittay 557 Public Culture I “three generations of imbeciles are enough.“’ The mentally retarded have at times been objects of pity, compassion, or abuse by their caretakers and society at large. But they have rarely been seen as subjects, as citizens, as persons with equal entitlement to fulfillment. Mental retardation comes to the public’s attention in sensational stories that expose appalling forms of abuse. We encountered the horror decades ago in Look magazine’s photo expose “Christmas in Purgatory” and, more recently, in the heavily illustrated article in the New York Times Muguzine showing conditions at Hidalgo in Guadalajara, Mexico, one of many “Global Willowbrooks” (Winerip 2000); or closer to home, in the Wushin@~n Post’s coverage of the unexplained and uninvestigated deaths of mentally retarded people living in the city-funded group homes of the nation’s capital (Vobejda 2000). And we gasp at the inhu- manity of those entrusted with the care of extremely vulnerable people. We won- der: How can this happen? How is it that we allow this to occur? Although we occasionally hear of these extreme cases of abuse, the victimiza- tion of severely intellectually disabled persons is more pervasive than these iso- lated examples suggest. Many individuals with mental retardation, especially when it is severe or profound or compounded by other disabilities, have been unaffected by the important strides made by other people with disabilities. Advo- cates of disability rights have insisted that the independence and productivity that are essential to being considered equal citizens in a liberal society are no less attainable for the disabled than for the nondisabled. They have argued that their impairments are only disabling in an environment that is hostile to their differ- ences and that has been constructed to exclude them. Yet, the impairment of men- tal retardation is not easily addressed by physical changes in the environment. Although a significant number of mentally disabled persons have been moved out of large state institutions into smaller, community-based facilities or independent apartments and are employed in supportive environments, most will need to be financially supported or to subsist on very low salaries. Of all disabled people, the severely mentally retarded have least benefited from the inclusion fought for by the disability community (Ferguson 1994). Perhaps this should not be surprising. The movement for the rights and inclu- sion of people with disabilities has followed a blueprint developed by persons of color, women, and gays and lesbians. All of these attempts by the marginalized to be recognized and fully enfranchised demanded that the practice of liberalism be 2. With this remark, Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes justified upholding the state’s right to deter- mine that Carrie Bell, a “feeble-minded woman” residing in a state institution, should be sterilized (Buck L: Bull, 274 U.S. 208 [1927]). 558 consistent with its tenets of universal equality and freedom. All the formerly When Caring Is Just and excluded have insisted on no longer being silenced, on having their voices heard. Justice Is Caring But for many with severe mental retardation, such a demand for voice appears futile. Even though other movements of inclusion have challenged the liberalism that they nonetheless invoked, the inclusion of people with mental retardation may well be liberalism’s limit case, just as it is a limiting case for the demands of many in the disability community. Liberalism invokes a notion of political partic- ipation in which one makes one’s voice heard. It depends on a conception of the person as independent, rational, and capable of self-sufficiency. And it holds to a conception of society as an association of such independent equals. Yet many with severe retardation cannot ever hope to be equal in these terms. Some, at least, may never be able to be independent or capable of participating in rational deliberation. Those who speak do so in a language not recognized-and even demeaned- by those who speak in the language of the public sphere. Without a claim to cog- nitive parity, even those who can speak are not recognized as authors or agents in their own right. Those who cannot speak must depend on others to speak for them. Those who can speak find that their voice is given no authority. Perhaps there is no more disabling disablement. To be heard, to be recognized, to have her needs and wants reckoned along with those of others, the mentally retarded individual requires an advocate-a role that has voice at its center. It is in the role of an advocate for my daughter, Sesha, that I enter into the field of “disability criticism.” I have wondered not only how and where I fit into this discourse; I have also considered how I interject my daughter into this critical discourse, into any public discourse. To do so, I must first tell the reader about her, for she cannot speak for herself. How do I describe Sesha? In speaking not only about her, but for her, I have already begun by describing her in the negative-as one who cannot speak for herself. Yet this lack is a synecdoche for all that she is unable to do: feed herself, dress herself, toilet herself, walk, talk, read, write, draw, say Mama or Papa. I would have preferred to start by speaking of her capabilities: the hugs and kisses she can give, her boundless enjoyment of the sensuous feel of water, or her abid- ing and profound appreciation of music. When asked about my daughter, I want to tell people that she is a beautiful, loving, joyful young woman. But then I need to tell them what she cannot be, given her profound cognitive limitations, her cerebral palsy, and her seizure disorders. When people ask how old my daughter is I always hesitate, wondering whether to give her chronological age and speak of her as a lovely and intense thirty-year-old woman, or to speak of the indeter- 559 Public Culture minate age that reflects her level of functioning and her total dependence. The positive set of responses is truer to who she is. Her limitations describe the face she shows to those who don’t know her, but they also convey the ways she cannot make her own way in the world. Knowing her capabilities, one gets a glimpse into the richness of her life and the remarkable quality of her very being. Nonetheless, the limitations shape her life and those of her family, so we all must address them if we are to make it possible for her beauty to flourish. Con- versely, only by considering her in the fullness of her joys and capacities can we view her impairments in light of her life, her interests, her happiness-and not as projections of her “able” parents or of an able-biased society. An exclusive focus on her limitations would set her outside liberal definitions of personhood and cit- izenship that are fixated on intellect, independence, and productivity. These val- ues throw into question her entitlement to the resources she needs for her full development and her flourishing. Advocating for the Cared-for by Advocating for the Carer Foremost among her needs is the need for care. If she is to flourish, she needs good caring care-and lots of it. Care is a multifaceted term. It is a labor, an atti- tude, and a virtue. As labor, it is the work of maintaining ourselves and others when we are in a condition of need. It is most noticed in its absence, most needed when it can be least reciprocated. As an attitude, caring denotes a positive, affec- tive bond and investment in another’s well-being. The labor can be done without the appropriate attitude. Yet without the attitude of care, the open responsiveness to another that is so essential to understanding what another requires is not pos- sible. That is, the labor unaccompanied by the attitude of care cannot be good care (see Kittay 1999). Good caring is cultivated as a virtue by some who can provide it for intimates and strangers alike. More frequently it is elicited when we are in an affectionate relationship with another. But even here, consistency of care, maintaining care even when it is difficult and disadvantageous to us, requires the cultivation of the virtue. Care as a virtue is a disposition manifested in caring behavior (the labor and attitude), in which “a shift takes place from the interest in our life situation to the situation of the other, the one in need of care” (Gastmans, Dierckx de Cast- erle, and Schotsmans 1998: 53). Since my daughter requires constant and attentive care, and because such care (the labor) requires devoted and caring caregivers (the attitude), to advocate for my daughter without also advocating for those who are entrusted with her well- 560 being is at once unjust and uncaring toward the caregiver. It also fails to accom- When Caring 1s Just and plish its original aim of assuring a good and fulfilling life for my daughter. This is Justice Is Caring so despite the fact that the interests of my daughter and those of her caregivers (whether me or others) are not always aligned, and that the interests of her paid caregivers are not infrequently at odds with those of her familial caregivers. To give voice to one who cannot speak, whose very agency appears so attenu- ated, means to pay the utmost heed to what 1 have called elsewhere the “depen- dency relation”: the relation between one who gives care and one who is depen- dent upon caregivers for her most basic life functions (“the charge”), a dependency that, while always socially shaped, is grounded in the inevitable circumstances of the human animal (see Kittay 1999).3 As a worker (elsewhere I speak of the “dependency worker”), the caregiver is vulnerable to exploitation. But because of the special demands of caregiving and because of the traditional assignment of this work to women or servants, depen- dency workers are more subject to exploitation than most. When paid, depen- dency work is rarely well paid. When done by family members, it is, as a rule, unpaid. Paid dependency workers are frequently drawn from classes or groups who are themselves relatively powerless within the society at large and who occupy a social status lower than that of their charge. As a result, even though the charge may be totally dependent on the dependency worker for the satisfaction of fundamental needs, the dependency worker may be vulnerable to those whose interests it serves to have the charge cared for, as well as to the actions of her charge. Conversely, given the dependency of the charge, or her physical or mental incapacity, the trust invested in the dependency worker not to abuse her power over the charge is enormous. The more stigmatized the condition that gives rise to the dependency and the more excluded and unvoiced the dependent is, the greater the opportunity and latitude for the dependency worker to violate that trust. It is conceivable that sheer coercion and policing could guarantee that a dependency worker charged with the care of a highly vulnerable person will not violate her trust and abuse her power over her charge. But the vigilance required makes such a means ineffectual in all but the most oppressive social conditions. More commonly, the emotional bond that forms between the caregiver and her charge secures the moral obligation to meet the needs of one who is vulnerable to your actions (Goodin 1985). The caregiver who has cultivated the virtue of care 3. Macintyre (1999) and Nussbaum (2000) tie our dependency to our continuity with other ani- m a l s . 561 Public Culture comes to view the interest of the charge as part of her own well-being. In the absence of some bonding or some attitudinal commitment, the care may be indif- ferent or even disastrously poor. Those who advocate for vulnerable persons must ask what conditions would encourage an attitude of care in the caregiver- all the while respecting the caregiver’s own needs and desires. Because good caregiving is inherently other directed, the agency of the good caregiver is not easily accommodated by the picture of the agent under liberal- ism, the rationally self-interested actor. Because the severely and profoundly mentally retarded are so dependent on the caregiver to exhibit other-directed behavior, the relationship between the two falls outside of conventional under- standings of relationships between equals within liberalism. The advocate for the severely retarded person needs to look beyond liberal- ism, while still respecting the values of autonomy and liberty propounded by lib- eral theory. She must seek conditions that are just to the caregiver as well as con- ducive to good care and justice for the charge. To advocate for caregivers is to insist that significant resources be set aside to pay for the services of caregivers, to provide them with the same benefits as other workers, to invest in training and the building of skills that will enable those who give care to help their charges develop all their capabilities. But why, a skeptic may ask, should we invest such resources (presumably pub- lic resources if they are to benefit all affected individuals) for the sake of a popu- lation that will never be able to reciprocate, whose material contributions will never match the outlay? We can demand such reciprocity from the subject of tra- ditional theories of liberal justice, but it makes little sense in the case of persons whose mental capabilities are very seriously limited. Charity or benevolence may motivate us to contribute to the care of such people, but is there any case to be made for the injustice of doing otherwise? Simply allowing those who cannot care for themselves to go unfed and unattended seems indecent. But do we have any duty to provide for their flourishing? We need therefore to ask what is due to the retarded, why it is due to them, and what is due to those who care for persons as dependent and vulnerable as my daughter and others like her. The Tradition of Personhood William Wordsworth, speaking of his poem “The Idiot Boy,” wrote of the “loathing and disgust” evoked by a person with mental retardation, and remarked that this is the consequence of a “want of comprehensiveness of thinking and feeling,” a “false delicacy” (De Selincort 1935: 295-96). Perhaps there will be a time when 562 we can rid people of the “false delicacy” and broaden the measure of thinking When Caring Is Just and and feeling to embrace a capacious concept of personhood. But it was not so in Justice Is Caring Wordsworth’s time, and it is not so now and here. Beauty may charm and physical prowess may awe, but intellect rules supreme. The intellect not only provides access to power and material goods. From Aris- totle to Rawls, it is by virtue of our intellect, our powers of rational deliberation, that humans acquire a unique moral status as well. For Aristotle, the possession of the deliberative faculty and ability to act from rational deliberation was the sine qua non for citizenship, an ability he attributed only to free men, not women and not slaves. The ascendance of humans’ rational capacities as the defining mark not only of citizenship but of personhood itself is illustrated by John Locke’s definition of a person as “a thinking intelligent being, that has reason and reflec- tion, and can consider itself as itself, the same thinking thing, in different times and places” (1987: 1.27.11). Persons, in turn, become the bearers of rights, the only signers of the social contract, the only actors in our morality plays, the only players to whom the rules of justice pertain, and so, the only ones for whom citi- zenship and justice are defined. Kant understood the dignity of humans to derive from their ability to assume duty through a law they themselves author. The capacity that elevates humans to the status of moral agents, he thought, is the rationality by which we judge if we can universalize maxims we choose for our own actions. Rational agency, he maintained, not our mere species membership, gives us the dignity of moral beings. Because we are capable of autonomy, of rationally determining what our duty is, we are due the respect of an end-in-itself, of an inhabitant of the kingdom of ends. Kant’s is a tradition that has endured; it finds especially influential expression today in the theory of justice advanced by John Rawls. Let us linger for a moment on Rawls, for his is the reigning theory of liberalism. Rawls understands justice to be due to those who enter with others into an association based on fair terms of cooperation. Those who are fully cooperating throughout their lives are the free and equal citizens of the well-ordered society. It is they who partake of both the benefits and burdens of social cooperation. Two moral powers, maintains Rawls, can be attributed to citizens who are both rational in recognizing and pursuing their own conception of the good (the first moral power) and reasonable in rec- ognizing the fairness of others also pursuing their own ends (the second moral power). It is the business of a just society to provide its citizens with the means to express these moral powers, that is, to pursue the good life as they see it and to allow others to pursue the good life as they see it. With Rawls’s theory of justice, 563 Public Culture free and equal agents in a fair procedure deliberate and choose the principles by which “primary goods” (the goods we require whatever our conception of the good is) are distributed through the basic institutions of society (Rawls 1980: 526). These goods presume and are determined by a conception of the person as possessing two moral powers, that is, as being both reasonable and rational. Where in this moral universe-and in a social/political world so repre- sented-is there room for those whose rational, reasonable, and reasoning capac- ities are impaired, perhaps severely? A conception of the primary goods is not tailored to their lives. It is not clear that their moral powers are adequately cap- tured in this picture of moral life, or that this conception of the moral powers is adequate to provide them with the protection, care, and resources they require to flourish (see Kittay 1999). Can moral citizenship be granted to those lacking such powers, powers presumed in the citizen who is “fully functioning throughout a life?’ (Rawls 1980: 546). What moral status does my daughter then have? If she has no place at the table of equal deliberators, of free and equal moral agents, of free and equal citizens, does justice apply to her?4 If traditional theories in the Western moral and political tradition are correct in their exclusion, then we have to wonder: When the heart cries “Injustice” upon encountering pictures of the mentally retarded tied to their beds, where one atten- dant cares for over one hundred entirely dependent residents (as in the “asylum” in Guadalajara), is this merely a misunderstanding of the term justice? When we read Nancy Scheper-Hughes’s (1992) vivid and sympathetic account of the abject lives of sugarcane workers of northeastern Brazil, of the numbed misery of the mothers who allow their weak (and doubtless impaired) infants to “return to Jesus” by failing to feed them, and believe that unjust circumstances compel these mothers to participate in a moral wrong (albeit one for which they are not the prime culprits)-are we merely foisting sentimental middle-class values on those who cannot afford them? And is there any ground for the accusation that the United States-the wealthiest nation in the history of the world-is unjust for not providing appropriate resources to families who lack means to properly care for their developmentally disabled child? Wealthy parents might, of course, choose to lavish care on their “deviant” family members, just as those with resources can lavishly spend on the many things for which there is no public sup- port. Similarly, a family who has resources to care for a child with Down syn- 4. Rawls, in fact, does not seem to think that the individual who is permanently impaired in such a way that he or she cannot fully participate in social cooperation throughout a life is not a citizen. See my discussion of this point in Kittay 1999: 105 n. 178. 564 drome might refuse prenatal testing and selective abortion. But should any fam- When Caring 1s Just and ily expect public support for such a child when an abortion would have been an Justice Is Caring inexpensive way to prevent such a birth‘? Are there any claims from justice to extend public provision for families to lighten the extra demands of raising a child with cognitive deficits so severe that no education or habilitation will turn that child into a future taxpayer? In the above discussion, we began thinking of the individual with intellectual disabilities, but we soon find ourselves including the family of which she is a part and her caregivers in our consideration. Earlier I spoke of caregivers as if they were different from the family and directed us to the vulnerability of the paid caregiver. But all caregivers, familial or paid, become derivatively dependent when they turn their time, attention, and concerns to a dependent other. And the greater the dependency of their charge,‘the greater their derivative dependency. Elsewhere I argue that not only are dependents effectively left out of the social contract, but dependency workers are implicitly excluded as well (Kittay 1999). Even as they advocate for their charge or other dependent kin, their own voice and the needs that arise from their role as caregivers come to be eclipsed. 1 asked above whether assistance to those who are dependent because of their permanent mental incapacity should expect support at the expense of the public. The same question could be asked of those who provide their care-even though the latter are surely capable of the full functioning that Rawls (1972, 1992) speaks of as requisite to membership in the community of equals. We can ask whether parents or kin who assume the role of caregiver should have claims on the larger society to support them in their efforts to provide care. If, for all the effort and care in raising a child with disabilities into adulthood, there is no payback (convention- ally understood) to the society at large, can we still insist that there be a state interest in helping families with the additional burdens of caring for a develop- mentally disabled child? Is there a state interest in assuring families that their vulnerable child will be well cared for when the family is no longer able or will- ing to do so? The Construction of Disability, the ADA, and Mental Retardation The enactment of the 1990 Americans with Disabilities Act (ADA) is an affirma- tion of the citizenship and the justice due to all disabled persons. That act, how- ever, does not try to establish the ground for affirming the personhood or citizen- ship of disabled Americans. It assumes it. Its point is to make discrimination based on disability illegal. Modeled on other antidiscrimination legislation, its 565 Public Culture approach is largely a negative one, stipulating that obstacles not be placed in the way of an individual’s opportunity to participate in the social cooperation consti- tutive of citizenship. As Anita Silvers (1998) argues, in the case of disability, a purely negative right not to be interfered with actually mandates positive action, such as the building of ramps and the modification of toilet facilities. Such positive action is largely com- pensatory, since the physiosocial environment might have been built so as not to exclude persons with differing abilities. Silvers makes the case that this approach supports the social model of disability rather than the medical model. The medical model locates the source of disability in the individual: the individual is defective and needs fixing; the social model locates the source of the disability in the social situation: the social situation requires fixing, not the individual. The supposition, endorsed by Silvers and adopted in some of the language of the ADA itself, is that once the barriers to full participation are removed, the disabled will be able to be as productive, self-sustaining, and independent as the abled. The focus on physical disabilities has given much plausibility to the arguments of the disability community that disadvantage, and the disability that results from a physiological impairment, is itself a consequence of an environment built to accommodate certain capacities but not others. Such an analysis of disability is especially applicable to physical disabilities, but may have some limited applica- bility to persons with a mild retardation as well. As a number of disability theo- rists and advocates have argued, it is only a consequence of our technologically advanced environment that we need to have skills that depend on very developed and trained cognitive capacities, skills beyond the capacities of mildly retarded persons. In an agrarian community, the mental abilities of a mildly retarded per- son may be quite sufficient to allow such an individual to live a reasonably inde- pendent and productive existence-a life that is viewed as normal. Even if this is true of very mildly retarded adults, there is no accommodation that transforms as severe a case of retardation as that of my daughter, Sesha, into a condition that is not profoundly disabling. The cognitive impairments of the severely and pro- foundly retarded are not merely contingently disabling. Unlike many disabilities, hers are not simply social constructions. Someone such as my daughter could not survive, much less thrive, without constant and vigilant attention, without some- one performing for her nearly all the tasks of daily living, as well as providing for her-and her caregiver-the material resources required for her existence and flourishing. We might say, however, that in the case of developmental disabilities, espe- 5 6 6 cially severe ones, though the disability itself is not socially constructed, the view When Caring Is Just and that mental retardation is a “problem” rather than a possible outcome of human Justice Is Caring physiology is. Those who have developmental disabilities require more supports than those without these impairments. However, they also provide different and rich opportunities for relationships and experiencing new ways of seeing the world (see Cushing and Lewis n.d., Bogdan and Taylor 1992, and Hingsburger ! 2000). Constructed only as a problem, Sesha and other developmentally disabled persons appear to have no claim to the aids and supports that they need to live and live well. According to some theories she is not a citizen of this or any coun- try.5 Must she and those who share her disabilities then be consigned to live off the scraps of a gratuitous and uncertain generosity? An Alternative Conception of Personhood In a recent essay, 1 contrast the lives of those shattered by inappropriate institu- tions and social neglect with that of Sesha. I evoke a morning in my kitchen when Sesha, accompanied by her caregiver, is having breakfast, and I sneak in to give her a kiss: Sesha, as always, is delighted to see me. Anxious to give me one of her distinctive kisses she tries to grab my hair to pull me to her mouth. Yet at the same time my kisses tickle her and make her giggle too hard to con- centrate on dropping the jam-covered toast before going after my hair. I negotiate, as best as I can, the sticky toast, the hair-pulling and the rasp- berry jam-covered mouth. In this charming dance, Sesha and I experience some of our most joyful moments-laughing, ducking, grabbing, kissing. (Kittay 2000b) They are “small” pleasures, to be sure, but pleasures that provide so much of life’s meaning and worth that they permit the deep sorrows of Sesha’s limitations to recede into a distant place in the mind; they are small joys, but are so profound that they even make me question that very sorrow. It is a pleasure both Sesha and I would have been denied if we could not share our lives together. Because we as a family have been able to keep Sesha in our home and com- munity, those who have made contact with her and have learned to see her as we who love her do have gained new perspectives on what it means to be a person. Seeing Sesha in her interactions with those who care for-and about-her 5. See Sachs 1999 for a report on the hurdles put in the way of persons with mental retardation and other mental disabilities by changes in the immigration law that took effect in 1994. 567 Public Culture reveals that being a person has little to do with rationality and everything to do with relationships-to our world and to those in it. If personhood is limited to those who possess certain intellectual capacities and to those who are productive, then my daughter would not be a person. But my daughter is a person. She is, after all, my daughter. How can she be anything but a person‘? If traditional conceptions of personhood are not capacious enough to include Sesha and those who share her impairments, we need a new definition. I propose that being a person means having the capacity to be in certain relation- ships with other persons, to sustain contact with other persons, to shape one’s own world and the world of others, and to have a life that another person can conceive of as an imaginative possibility for him- or herself (see Diamond 1991). It is a def- inition that brings our relationships (real and imaginative) with others to the center of any conception of personhood. We do not become a person without the engagement of other persons-their care, as well as their recognition of the uniqueness and the connectedness of our human agency,6 and the distinctiveness of our particularly human relations to others and of the world we fashion.7 The shaping of one’s own world is a gift that each individual possesses and that some make more use of than others. Sesha, in spite of all her limitations, makes ample use of this gift. To be with Sesha is to enter her orbit, to gain a glimpse of the world as she constructs it. Even those who are still more limited than Sesha have this capacity. It requires an openness to experience it. In one who can scarcely move a muscle, a glint in the eye at a strain of familiar music estab- lishes personhood. A slight upturn of the lip in a profoundly and multiply disabled individual when a favorite caregiver comes along, or a look of joy in response to the scent of a perfume-all these establish personhood. We know that there is a person before us when we see, as David Hingsburger (2000: 24) says, that there is “someone home”; that the seemingly vacuous look is not vacant at all; that an individual’s inability to articulate a “language” as publicly defined does not indi- cate a lack of anything to say. To fail to recognize that capacity is to deny an indi- vidual’s personhood. When we do so, we cut ourselves off from those who enlarge our relational possibilities, and we lessen ourselves as persons. Keeping Sesha at home would not have been possible without an extensive and costly support system. Without these neither Sesha, nor her family, nor those 6. See Becker 2000 for an account of the good of agency and the ADA. 7. I take species membership to be central to our understanding of personhood, as does Diamond (1991). The kiss I share with another human is distinctively human. 1 argue that to reduce what makes us persons to a set of defined characteristics is a mistake. See Kittay 2000a. 568 Public Culture be made to partake in one tiny step in an assembly line production, and she is given some material compensation, we would call this “working” and being “pro- ductive”-whether or not this activity has any meaning for her.8 To so stretch these concepts both empties them of meaning and undermines the possibility that dignity is compatible with life-long dependency. It means that when a disabled person requires attendants to help her dress, assist her mobility, or monitor a medical disability-related condition in order to be “independent,” we mask a gen- uine dependency. But who in any complex society is not dependent on others, for the production of our food, for our mobility, for a multitude of tasks that make it possible for each of us to function in our work and daily living? Many of these dependencies are hidden, as when we fail to think about our dependence on those who grow our food. Other dependencies are hypervisible, such as the dependence that results from certain disabilities or the dependence on state support of poor, single moth- ers who cannot simultaneously be employed (at minimum wage) and care for young or disabled children. But dependence that goes unacknowledged is still not independence. Independence, except in some particular actions and functions, is a fiction, regardless of our abilities or disabilities, and the pernicious effects of this fiction are encouraged when we hide the ways in which our needs are met in relations of dependencies. On the other hand, this fiction turns those whose dependence can- not be masked into pariahs, or makes them objects of disdain or pity. It causes us to refuse assistance when it is needed. It encourages us either to deny that assis- tance to others when they require it or to be givers of care because we fear hav- ing to receive care ourselves. In acknowledging dependency we respect the fact that as individuals our dependency relations are constitutive of who we are and that, as a society, we are inextricably dependent on one another. I suggest that it is preferable to refuse the contractarian basis for the distribution of benefits and burdens (that only those who assume their share of society’s burdens are due a fair share of the benefits) and with it the myth of independence and an overem- phasis on rationality. In acknowledging dependency we can borrow from what is best in Marx: that benefits and burdens are to be assigned by need and capability, respectively (cf. Nussbaum 2000). Behind the ADA and the prohibition of discrimination is the deeper concept that physical or mental impairments should not result in lives devoid of the satis- factions for which we all yearn and which make life worth living. The satisfaction 8. These are all interpretations that I have, in fact, heard applied to very severely retarded adults. 570 of those yearnings may take forms that are distinctive, but the disabled person- When Caring Is Just and even when profoundly mentally retarded-is as entitled to them as the nondis- Justice Is Caring abled. The principle that the disabled are as entitled as the nondisabled should not be held hostage to a notion that a disabled person must become “productive” or live “independently” if “suitably assisted,” or that it is less costly to place an indi- vidual in a community rather than an institution. Supporting the Caregiver-Justly The appalling conditions found in the global Willowbrooks, of which the psychi- atric hospital in Mexico is only one example, are part of the history we thought we left behind when we moved large numbers of institutional residents into group homes. But the mistreatment, which largely had been attributed to the systemic inadequacies of what Goffman (1961) had called “total institutions,” has resur- faced in group homes. The headline in the Washington Post announcing the crim- inal conduct of those who run many of the group homes in Washington, D.C., and the callousness and indifference of some of the staff, testify to the persistent nature of the problem of good care for the mentally retarded. And this case is only one among many (see Ohlemacher 2000, Tully 1999, and Boo 1999). In “a society which defines and confines all meaning and worth in terms of production, profit, and pervasive greed,” writes James Trent in his history of men- tal retardation, the intellectually disabled will be exploited (1994: 277). In such a society, their caretakers will also be exploited and will have the opportunity to become victimizers as well as victims. The change from institution to group home can help, but the form of the residence will not alter the poor care its residents receive if the caregivers are as abject as their charges. In such a society, care will be minimal, and callous caretakers will be inevitable. Family Dependency Work The home may not always be “a haven in a heartless world,” but for the very vulnerable, connections with family members are often the only shield against the slings and arrows of an uncaring society. Family mem- bers are often, but not only (and not always), those whose ties are biological or legal, but are those “who by birth, adoption, marriage, or declared commitment share a deep personal connection and are mutually entitled to receive and oblig- ated to provide support of various kinds to the extent possible, especially in times of need” (Levine 1990). In the United States as well as in most other nations, state support for families who want to keep their family member home is far too limited and tends to be 5 7 1 Public Culture means-tested, providing relief only for families who are below a certain income. As one researcher states, “when programs are limited in scope and size, return- ing a person with disabilities to the community may be a euphemism for return- ing the child to the mother” (Nemzoff 1992: 20). Affluent as well as poor fami- lies find themselves overwhelmed with medical and caretaking responsibilities. The Kelso family, the father a CEO and the mother an activist for disabled peo- ple, made the front page of newspapers across the country when they abandoned their multiply disabled and medically fragile young son in a hospital during the Christmas holidays, when relief caregivers were in very short supply (Jacobs 1999).9 Given the circumstances families face, it is hardly a wonder that when families decide to place their child in residential care, there is an estrangement-an estrangement that comes with the relief of a burden too heavy to bear.10 In group homes within the community there is a better likelihood that the protective con- nections will be retained, but not for individuals whose families have already lost touch. When families disappear from the scene, there are few who provide the oversight to assure that residents are not neglected or abused. The weight of the burden that causes the estrangement is less a function of the impairment per se than of the larger society’s failure to help the family in its efforts to care for its disabled relative. Although familial caregivers are as capable of neglect and abuse as strangers paid to care,” affective bonds that normally form between family members offer important defenses against the harmful behavior, especially when supports are available to ease hardships. It would seem that expenditures that aided mothers, fathers, grandmothers, and other family members who do the dependency work or continue to assume dependency responsibilities even when their relative is in residential care would be especially well spent. Paid Dependency Workers If unpaid familial caregivers need assistance in main- taining their relationship to their mentally disabled family member and keeping ties alive for the long haul, caregivers who do their work for pay need support in 9. Manning 2000 places the Kelso case into the context of others raising children with serious medical and mental disabilities. 10. Reported in discussion with the director of the Sullivan County Diagnostic Center in Sullivan County, New York. 11. See Bonner and Rimer 2000 for a report on Johnny Paul Penry, a retarded man and convicted rapist and murderer in Texas, who suffered abuse at the hands of his mother. 572 Public Culture With one stroke, dependents-be they small children or incapacitated adults, be the impairments physical or mental-become an integral part of any social organization. To presume that they stand outside of justice, that they are not enti- tled, that-for reasons of their impairments and dependence-they lack rights, seems odd indeed if the point and purpose of such principles (if not the sole one) is a social order that secures the ability to care for dependents. Inevitable dependencies, the dependencies of our early years, old age, disabil- ity, and illness, however, have been privatized, so that we have come to discount them and the integral part of social life they in fact constitute. Doing so permits us to avoid our collective responsibility to maintain dependents. We forget the extent to which we need social organization to assure that should we become dependent, we will have the assistance we need, and to assure that should we have to care for dependents, we ourselves will not come to bear the full burden and become unable to meet our own needs. Not all of us will remain in a state of dependency as profound as that of my daughter. But any of us could become so- an illness or an accident could make us so. From the vantage point of our socially constructed independence, we might think, “Oh, but should that happen, I would rather be dead.” From the vantage point of my daughter, that is wasteful of what life has to offer, a failure to appreciate the gifts of being. Within the reigning liberal understanding of justice, we must continue to think of those with severe or profound cognitive disabilities as exceptional, as those who can never be citizens, whom we will care for out of compassion (or pity?), and who have no rights associated with their needs. If we meet their needs, it is out of a gratuitous kindness, a kindness they have no right to demand. As “excep- tions” then, those with profound developmental and cognitive impairments are vulnerable to the vicissitudes, indignities, and stigma of being passive recipients of charity. However, it may be that calling for charity and benevolence is sufficient for protecting this portion of the disabled population from neglect and abuse, that it is unnecessary to overhaul long-standing treatments of justice because they exclude the retarded. Can’t we argue from benevolence and charity that the men- tally retarded should not be neglected and abused? Indeed, to invoke “the stigma of being passive recipients of charity” and to speak, as I did earlier, of generosity as uncertain and gratuitous may be prejudicing the case and may be mere rhetoric. Is charity really inadequate? Why insist on a full-blown notion of personhood or citizenship to cover those whom so many have so long viewed as falling short, as inappropriate subjects for justice? Let us concede, for the sake of argument, that the severely retarded do not 574 have claims to citizenship and may not even be persons. Sti]], they should not be When Caring Is Just and harmed, because doing SO diminishes those in the larger society who would do Justice Is Caring the harm or allow the harm. Just as cruelty to animals may be immoral not because of what it does to the animal, but because of what it does to those who inflict the cruelty, so we should not be cruel to the mentally retarded. Is this not sufficient to protect the severely retarded from neglect and abuse? If such thinking is the basis for providing aid, the aid will, of necessity, be a low priority in any public distribution of resources. It will tend to be minimal, except in cases in which individual acts of generosity surface. But if such support is minimal, those who do the dependency work for this population will, as is now the case, be only minimally rewarded for their labors. The respect they gain for their work will be similarly minimal. The low pay and lack of respect will encour- age the conditions that breed the neglect and abuse that calls for charity and benevolence were intended to counter. For nonhuman animals it may be sufficient to invoke the principle that harm inflicted on them is wrong because of what it does to those who do the injury. Nonhuman animals can fend for themselves, if they are not harmed or interfered with by humans. But the fate of human beings who are impaired is intimately tied in with other humans-especially those who provide care. Not being harmed is only part of what we require when we are dependent, and the lack of care-the full-blown sort, not the labor mechanically carried out-is equivalent to harm. How the care is bestowed makes all the difference between the potential for harm and spirit-sustaining aid. Care is a costly morality: costly in the personal and emotional resources it demands and in the time it consumes (time that cannot be devoted to investing in a career or advancing oneself materially). When care is not adequately sup- ported, either the cost of care is borne by the caregiver alone or the charge fails to receive adequate care-or both suffer. If the retarded person should be treated with charity and benevolence because she should not be harmed, then she must be treated with an enlarged concept of justice-a justice large enough to embrace her and her (familial and nonfamilial) caregivers-that gives a right to care and support for care. Only then can the most vulnerable of disabled people hope to be safe and able to develop and flourish as persons in a just and caring society. To stigmatize dependency, ignore its frequency, and valorize only a particular segment of human possibility is to shirk our collective responsibility to take care of one another and to ensure that we are well taken care of by someone for whom our well-being matters deeply. Looking at justice through a lens of social con- structionism that only sees dependence as constructed and fails to see indepen- 575 Public Culture dence as still more constructed will only reinstate prejudices against disability. This time the prejudice falls most heavily on the shoulders of the severely and profoundly mentally retarded, who are the most vulnerable and whose enormous dependencies cannot be nullified by environmental modifications. But we exclude them from justice at a cost. That cost is the denial of the dependent animals we are. It is a condition no amount of rationality can alter. Although care seems to have less in common with rights and justice than with virtues and benevolence, the virtue and kind hand of care requires a just setting in which to blossom. In a context of condescending pity (toward the mentally impaired dependent) and exploitative demands (toward the dependency worker), the inequality between dependent and dependency worker too easily fosters dom- ination rather than caring. In a society ruled by the conceptions of liberalism, where rights are “trump cards,” charity and benevolence can never replace the guarantees of human dignity that entitlements of justice provide. In the end, this may be the great achievement of liberalism. It is one that we cannot forgo, no matter how much we challenge liberalism in our hope for a more progressive, a more inclusive, and a more caring political vision than it now provides. Justice that is caring begins with an acknowledgment of our dependency and seeks to organize society so that our well-being is not inversely related to our need for care or to care; such justice makes caring itself a mode of just action. Coda-An Acknowledgment For my daughter, dependence of the most profound sort will be part of her normal existence. But such dependence does not preclude a certain form of mutual depen- dence. I depend on her as well. Sesha and her well-being are essential to my own. Her smile chases away the trivial distractions of the day. Her embrace grounds me in what is important and precious. Watching her grow and develop skills and take pride in her accomplishments nurtures me as much as my own work. In another place I’ve written: “It’s perhaps self-delusional to say that I am as depen- dent on her as she is on me, but perhaps not. Others could take care of her and even love her-in fact, I must think that she will continue to thrive with or with- out me. But without her, I would wither” (Kittay 2000b). Writing that passage, acknowledging that I was even more dependent on her than she on me was itself a moment of discovery. Although my daughter can never be “productive” or pay back to society any- thing of material value, still her contributions are great. Her sweetness radiates and enriches the lives of everyone she touches, those who allow themselves to be 576 touched by her. Without her abundant and exuberant love, the world would be a W h e n C a r i n g I s J u s t a n d more dismal place. I am only beginning to fill volumes with what I have learned Justice Is Caring from her. Eva Feder Kittay is a professor of philosophy at the State University of New York at Stony Brook. Her most recent book is Love’s Labor: Essays on Women, Depen- dency, and Equality (1999). References Becker, Lawrence C. 2000. The good of agency. In Americans with disabilities: Exploring implications of law for individuals and institutions, edited by Leslie Pickering Francis and Anita Silvers. New York: Routledge. Bogdan, Robert, and Steven J. Taylor. 1992. The social construction of human- ness. In Interpreting disability: A qualitative reader, edited by Philip M. Fer- guson, Diane L. Ferguson, and Steven J. Taylor. New York: Teachers College Press. Bonner, Raymond, and Sara Rimer. 2000. Mentally retarded man facing Texas execution draws wide attention. New York Times, 12 November, A 1. Boo, Katherine. 1999. Invisible lives: Troubled system for the retarded. Wash- ington Post, 5 December, Al, 3. Cushing, Pamela, and Tanya Lewis. N.d. Negotiating mutuality and agency in care-giving relationships with women with intellectual disabilities. Unpub- lished manuscript. De Selincourt, Ernest, ed. 1935. The early letters of William and Dorothy Words- worth (1787-1805), 295-96. Oxford: Clarendon. Quoted in James W. Trent, The invention of the feeble mind (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1995), 9. Diamond, Cora. 1991. The importance of being human. In Human beings, edited by David Cockbum. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Ferguson, Philip M. 1994. Abandoned to their fate: Social policy and practices toward severely retarded people in America. Philadelphia: Temple University Press. Gastmans, Chris, Bernadette Dierckx de Casterle, and Paul Schotsmans. 1998. Nursing considered as moral practice: A philosophical-ethical interpretation of nursing. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 8: 43-69. Goffman, Erving. 1961. Asylum: Essays on the social situation of mental patients and other inmates. New York: Anchor. 577 Public Culture Goodin, Robert. 1985. Protecting the vulneruble: A reanalysis of our social responsibilities. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Hingsburger, David. 2000. First contact: Charting inner space. Quebec: Diverse City. Jacobs, Andrew. 1999. Pennsylvania couple accused of abandoning disabled son. New York Times, 31 December, Al. Kittay, Eva F. 1999. Love’s labor: Essuys on equality, women, and dependency. New York: Routledge. -. 2000a. Relationality, impairment and Peter Singer on the fate of severely impaired infants. APA Newsletter on Philosophy and Medicine 99: 253-56. -. 2000b. At home with my daughter. In Americans with disabilities, edited by Leslie Pickering Francis and Anita Silvers. New York: Routledge. Levine, Carol. 1990. AIDS and changing concepts of the family. The Milbunk Quarterly 68: 33-57. Locke, John. 1987. An essay concerning human understunding. Edited with a foreword by Peter H. Nidditch. New York: Oxford University Press. Macintyre, Alisdair. 1999. Dependent rutional animals. Peru, Ill.: Carus. Manning, Anita. 2000. Quietly overwhelmed. USA Today, 17 January, Al. Nemzoff, Ruth, E. 1992. Changing perceptions of mothers of children with devel- opmental disabilities 1960- 1992: A critical review. Working Paper. Working Paper Series. Center on Research on Women: Wellesley College, Wellesley, Mass. Nussbaum, Martha C. 2000. The future of feminist liberalism. Presidential address given at the annual meeting of the American Philosophical Associa- tion, Central Division, Chicago, 22 April. Ohlemacher, Stephen. 2000. Retarded patients lack protection, study finds. Cleve- land Plain Dealer, 8 January, 1 A. Rawls, John. 1972. A theory ofjustice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. -. 1980. Kantian constructivism in moral theory: The Dewey lectures 1980. Journal ofPhilosophy 77: 515-72. ---. 1992. Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press. Sachs, Susan. 1999. An I.N.S. hurdle for the disabled: Promised exemptions elude many would-be citizens. New York Times, 18 February, B 1. Scheper-Hughes, Nancy. 1992. Deuth without weeping: The violence of everyday life in Brazil. Berkeley: University of California Press. Silvers, Anita, David Wasserman, and Mary Mahowald. 1998. Disability, difer- ence, discrimination. Lanham, Md.: Rowman and Littlefield. 578 Trent, James W. 1994. The invention of the feeble mind. Berkeley: University of California Press. Tully, Tracy. 1999. Retarded are found living in squalor. New York Daily News, 12 July, A7. Vobejda, Barbara. 2000. City wards face daily indignities: Documents illustrate the suffering of mentally retarded in D.C. system. Washington Post, 15 Febru- ary, Al. Wertz, Dorothy. 2000. Drawing the line. In The ethics of prenatul testing and selective abortion: A report from the Hastings Center. edited by Adrienne Asch and Eric Parens. Philadelphia: Temple University Press. Winerip, Michael. 2000. The global Willowbrook. New York Times Magazine, 16 January, 58-67. When Caring Is Just and Justice Is Caring 579 work_dog4auai4vgt5f23dqihnevp2m ---- Notes and News. 481 would sooner divest themselves; and the best way to encourage crime of the worst character in the reading ranks of life is to promulgate the " couldn't help it " doctrine, taking care to invest it with the authority of science. Constance Kent's confession completely brushes away all the fine-spun cobwebs which pseudo- philanthropists and philosophers have been spinning about her case. The culprit owns her motive—the old-fashioned one of jealousy and revenge—and describes the consummate craft, subtlety, and cruelty with which she accomplished her purpose—a purpose which she had nursed for a long period, and which she would never have confessed had not her dormant better nature—of which no human being is utterly destitute—been awakened by the teachings of religion. Dr. Bucknill, whilst he throws any suspicion of insanity iu the case to the winds, yet thinks* " that, owing to the peculiarities of her constitution, it is probable that under prolonged solitary confinement she would become insane." He goes on to say that " the validity of this opinion is of importance now that the sen tence of death has been commuted to penal servitude for life ; for no one could desire that the punishment of the criminal should be so carried out as to cause danger of a further and greater punishment not contemplated by law." We are quite ready to concede to Dr. Buckuill that Miss Constance Kent's history shows that she has "a peculiarity of disposition" which seems to us, however, to be peculiar only in strength of will and depravity ; but that, because her early girlhood was blackened by a great crime, conspicuous for the coolness, determination, and circumspection with which it was executed, she is more likely to go mad than other criminals, we do not see. AYe sincerely hope that the accounts we have heard of Constance Kent's peni tence may be true, but we should be sorry to see her let loose on society on the ground that insanity might be produced by pro longed confinement. There is really but one party to be con sidered in the matter. Public safety and public justice require that such criminals as Miss Kent should not only be punished, but restrained from committing further crimes. Although in the course of their punishment insanity should arise, the infliction of a just sentence is not to be suspended or relaxed on such a possibility. We may also remind Dr. Bucknill that penal servitude and solitary confinement for life are by no means one and the same thing.—Medical Times and Gazelle, Sept. 2nd. Justice to Criminal Lunatics. On the 29th July, we commented on the case of George Broom- field, who had been tried for murder and left for execution—the 432 Notes and News. man being a manifest lunatic. Notwithstanding his trial by judge and jury, the man has since been reprieved and converted into a criminal lunatic. Again, on August 3rd, a man was tried for murder of his wife. The crime of murder, and the responsibility of the murderer, according to law, were as certain and clear in this case as in the case of Broomfield ; but Mr. Justice Montague Smith saw the case in a different light from the judge who tried Broomfield, and actually stopped the trial ; and the man was ac quitted on the ground of insanity. We venture to think that, in both these cases, there is a grievous miscarriage of justice ; and that the conclusions arrived at in both cases must tend to bring judge and jury and criminal law into disrepute. In the case of Broomfield, the man, after being tried by judge and jury, is again tried by a Government expert (whose name even does not appear) ; and by the sentence of this expert is upset the solemn verdict of the jury. This sort of upsetting of justice is becoming an everyday oc currence ; and it will continue to be so, until Government has the good sense to send an expert in lunacy to examine and give evi dence in court concerning the mental condition of criminals, who are supposed to be, or who are, lunatic. What can be more outrageous to reason and justice—more brutal, we might say—than to throw upon a lunatic the onus probandi his lunatic state of mind ? What, again, can be more dissonant from our English idea of administering justice, than that the verdict of the jury should be reconsidered and settled after trial by an unknown and irresponsible lunacy expert ? What can more tend to throw the opinions of judges and the verdict of juries into disrepute—to render justice uncertain—than the fact that, after the solemn judicial trial of a criminal, he is to be tried again in private by an individual who is responsible to no court of law ? Is it not a scandal to our laws that cases of such kind should be now of constant occurrence? Smethurst, for example, was condemned to death by judge and jury ; but his fate was finally decided by a report of the late Sir B. Brodie, who thus revised the jury's verdict ! Consider, again, the scandal of Townley's case. He is first made a lunatic by the jury and sent to a lunatic asylum ; and afterwards declared sane by Government experts, and sent from the lunatic asylum into penal servitude for life. All such constantly recurring scandals to justice can be prevented by making the impartial Government expert give his evidence in court during the trial, and, therefore, of course, before the jury deliver their verdict. Such a course of proceeding is demanded by humanity as well as by justice. Humanity requires that a skilled and impartial inquirer should investigate and report upon the con dition of supposed criminal lunatics; and save them—if they be Notes and News. 433 really lunatic in the eyes of science—from the hangman's hands. Why should a poverty-stricken wretch be put in a worse position than the rich criminal who is able to fee heavily some high authority in lunacy ? And again, justice demands, on the other side, that criminals who have the means of paying heavy fees in order to bring witnesses with high names into court, should not thereby escape the just reward of their crimes. Justice demands that, in suoli cases also, an impartial Government expert should be there to counteract the evidence of the authoritative names; i.e., if the evidence be guided by party considerations rather than by the actual facts of the case.—British Medical Journal, Sept. 2nd. The Legal View of Insanity. To the Editor of ' The Lancet.' SIR,—At Winchester, on July 16th, George Broomfield was found guilty of murder. He was ably defended by Mr. Coleridge, Q.C., on the ground of insanity. It was proved in evidence that two years previously he had been shot in the head, and had since been a "changed man;" that he had delusions and suicidal im pulses ; and that at this moment he is half dead from the effects of a shot-wound inflicted upon himself. The counsel for the crown made no attempt to rebut the evidence of Dr. Tweed, and that of a crowd of other witnesses who deposed to the insanity of the prisoner; nevertheless the learned judge, in his summing-up, told the jury that " it was not every aberration of mind that would free the prisoner— it must be such an aberration of intellect as to disable him from distinguishing between right and wrong." Under this ruling the jury returned a verdict of " guilty," and the poor, lunatic cri minal, whose own only plea was, " I wish to die," is duly sentenced to be hanged. The same eloquent counsel, before the same judge, will, on Saturday, plead in behalf of Miss Constance Kent. It is possible that in her case the defence of insanity may be set up, and may be equally justified ; nevertheless it is clear that, whether insane or not, she must be condemned to death on her own confession, by making which she herself shows her full appreciation and knowledge of the difference between right and wrong. Surely there must be some grave mistake as to the value of a test that inevitably sends the possibly insane daughter of an insane mother to die upon the scaffold. That it is practically fallacious must be shown by the fact that, standing by her side, condemned in the same week by the same judge, will be found another unhappy homicide, admittedly suffering under mental disease arising from physical injury to the brain, work_drnpyrtgfzdxzj732z5htznzve ---- The Journal of Teaching and Learning, Fall 2018 Vol. 12, No. 1, pp. 59–62 http://www.uwindsor.ca/jtl 59 Book Review: Transforming Teacher Education for Social Justice by By Eva Zygmunt and Patricia Clark, with Jon Clausen, Wilfridah Mucherah, and Susan Tancock New York, NY: Teachers College Press, 2016, 138 pages ISBN: 978-0-8077-5708-6 (Paperback) Reviewed by: Oluseyi Matthew Odebiyi University of Alabama The uncertainties in the current dichotomized social and political climate necessitate a new way of thinking about quality teacher improvement. Crafting this dynamic way of thinking has become the central focus of teacher education with a focus on improving instructional competencies of future teachers in handling hot-point issues such as diversity in lived experience, religion, culture, and race to mention a few. Teacher education programs increasingly focus on how future teachers can create equitable and democratic approaches, and incorporate the lived experiences of historically marginalized students and create an opportunity for all students to become participatory global citizens. Zygmunt, Clark, Clausen, Mucherah, and Tancock’s (2016) book Transforming Teacher Education for Social Justice, draws on research to examine the relationship among the nature of teacher education, quality of teachers, and the dimension of experience provided for marginalized students. The book proffers an alternative to the ideological inconsistencies inherent in traditional teacher education while simultaneously addressing the perpetuated inequity and social injustice in public school classrooms. The book advocates for a social justice-based immersive teacher residency model tagged “schools within the context of community” (p. 9). Teacher candidates are educated within and immersed in the lived experiences of the community settings where young learners live and learn, an approach that is beyond the traditional teacher preparation. This social justice-oriented teacher education provides a framework for restructuring and actualizing the need for change in teacher education programs’ focus on strategies for addressing disadvantaged public schools from seemingly difficult structural change to improving teacher quality (Takayama, Jones, & Amazan, 2017). Unlike the current traditional teacher education practice of strictly sending http://www.uwindsor.ca/jtl Book Review: Transforming Teacher Education for Social Justice Journal of Teaching and Learning 12(1) 60 teacher candidates to various cultural communities without prior negotiation and mediation, the book elucidates intentional engagement of community expertise and wisdom in the training of future educators for effective practice. The book has six chapters. The first chapter examines an inclusive collaborative approach to situated learning in the community of practice. It discusses in detail the theoretical and structural frameworks for schools within the context of community. The immersion program provides teacher candidates the concrete experience of understanding the contextual complexities of the environment beyond the classroom. Notably, the book speaks to the heart of the needed mediation between huge classroom diversities and teaching practices. The book provokes readers to contemplate questions such as, how can teacher preparation programs develop in future teachers the pedagogical competencies and dispositions to address differential personal experiences of marginalized students through a socially just model? This approach to teacher education provides reciprocal ways out from intense navigation of agency for both teacher and students (Bamberg, De Fina, & Schiffrin, 2011; Sunal & Haas, 2008). Chapter two focuses on a community-based interdisciplinary approach that current traditional teacher education programs can leverage to connect their formal and structural perspectives to community conceptual perspectives of teacher education that integrate content, pedagogy, and practice. Pivotal to social justice, teacher education is the promotion of multidimensional meanings, active engagement, and partnership among teacher preparation colleges, schools, and communities. Supported by groundbreaking research, chapter three explicitly describes how community teachers can be developed in line with the schools within the context of community framework. Remarkably, this chapter establishes a deviation from the common practice of textbooks presenting only the theory and aggregated view of how teacher preparation works (Odebiyi & Mansouri, 2017). The book provides details from actual practice on developing teachers that are conscious of the community and promote social justice. Explicating the sustainability, the model is ongoing and implemented intentionally to train teachers who connect formal curriculum, instruction, and assessment to young learners’ lived experience. Arguably, these capacity building experiences helped the teacher candidates to better serve diverse students and meet each community on their own terms. Chapters four and five jointly describe the effects of the social justice residency model on the teacher education program, teacher educators, teacher candidates, the students and the host community. The description of the teacher candidates’ pedagogical and dispositional successes is compelling. Various data speak to the achievement of educating teachers for social justice. Achievements include the ability of program graduates to identify and respond to critical incidences, as well as a highlighting of how future teacher would be able to synthesize learning, develop strong self-efficacy, and transition from the teacher education program to practice without difficulties. As per students’ learning and behavior, the evidence provided in this book convincingly explains how the university-school-community partnerships help improve school culture and students’ behavior and learning. Finally, chapter six is a form of appeal to teacher education programs to adopt or adapt the social justice approach to teacher preparation. Given the current climate of uncertainties, the Journal of Teaching and Learning 12(1) O. M. Odebiyi 61 authors advance that social justice-based teacher education represents a paradigm for a great teacher education program because moral and ethical codes guide teachers and inform their daily decisions. Teacher educators and teacher candidates are challenged to contribute to the community and students’ learning by developing an understanding of the community conditions and addressing the learning needs of their students while working alongside members of the community. This way, teacher educators and teacher candidates get acquainted with the contextual and systematic structures that inhibit the work of social change in marginalized communities. The framework for developing and implementing social justice teacher education in this book is research-based, however, the authors did not provide enough caution that its implementation does not guarantee in all cases the preparation of future teachers whose practice would exemplify social justice. In addition, the book does not draw a clear line between social justice, culturally relevant pedagogy, and culturally responsive pedagogy. The book assumes equivalence in meanings for these constructs. Scholars in these areas may not necessarily agree with such equivalence, hence understanding the book's framework may become controversial and mislead readers—especially those who are not conversant with the specified fields. Educating teacher candidates for social justice is more important now than ever before because of the conflict between the growing diversities among learners and the failure of nations to educate children equitably. Transforming Teacher Education for Social Justice would be a beneficial resource for educators, researchers, policymakers, and readers who believe in social justice. It would be a good starting point for educators and practitioners who want to learn about a practical way of incorporating social justice into teacher education programs and practices to further the course of social justice in classrooms. Practitioners and researchers can learn from the practical explanation offered by the book on how teacher educators and teacher candidates can align theoretical knowledge with, and be more actively engaged in, the knowledge construction and meaning-making experiences of students and communities. Researchers in teacher education would find the framework useful to adapt because of its flexibilities to suit different programs and communities. The authors demonstrate the adequate ethical value of openness by offering the required level of commitment for successful implementation of the social justice model. If properly adopted, the perspective advanced in the book would deliver the promise of an equitable and socially just learning opportunity that is the hallmark of public education, one which everyone in educational studies is pursuing. References Bamberg, M., De Fina, A., & Schiffrin, D. (2011). Discourse and identity construction. In Schwartz, S. J., K., Luyckx & V. L., Vignoles (Eds.). Handbook of identity theory and research (pp. 177-199). New York, NY: Springer. Odebiyi, O. M., & Mansouri, B. (2017). Looking through the social studies textbooks with activity type lenses. GATEways to Teacher Education, 28(1), 1-9. Sunal, C. S., & Haas, M. E. (2008). Social studies for the elementary and middle grades: A constructivist approach (3rd ed.). Boston, MA: Pearson. Book Review: Transforming Teacher Education for Social Justice Journal of Teaching and Learning 12(1) 62 Takayama, K., Jones, T., & Amazan, R. (2017). Thinking with/through the contradictions of social justice in teacher education: Self-reflection on NETDS experience. Australian Journal of Teacher Education, 42(4), 83-96. work_duwdnv42frdxvhwapzeyhnuf3q ---- Charles R. Menzies New Proposals Editorial Collective Introduction New Proposals: Journal of Marxism and Interdisciplinary Inquiry Vol. 7, No. 2 (March 2015) Pp. 5-6 On the cover of this issue of the journal is a photo taken in the wheelhouse of a coastal British Columbia fishboat. It is dark out, the image is not in sharp focus, the man on the wheel is staring up at an electronic map display, and we can’t see forward through the vessel’s windows. For those familiar with navigational electronics you will know that the green display is of a GPS (Global Positioning System) assisted chart plotter. It shows where one is and aids in finding the way towards one’s destination. On a vessel of this size we also had a radar that helped show other vessels moving around us, radios provid- ing information on weather conditions, and devices to tell us how deep the water was underneath the boat’s hull. All of that is meaningless, of course, if we didn’t also know how to interpret the informa- tion. All of that electronic data is then compared with the sounds we hear and what we see when we open a wheelhouse window and peer forward into the dark, rainy night. Early navigators travelling through these same waterways millennia ago did not have our electronic instruments. They did share a similar understanding of the physical sense of navigation and observational skills required to move through unfamiliar terrain. The old histories of navigating through these waters include references to landmarks and currents that remain familiar to us today. Yet we see them slightly differently and we use them to purposes somewhat different than our predecessors did. We remain intent, however, upon finding our way from one point to another. Łagyigyet, the old people or ancestors, made their lives in these waters. They struggled to find a balance between themselves and their human needs and the other social beings that inhabited these waters. While their world was not perfect, it was a world in which a certain sense of social justice pervaded. When the people lost their way from the path retribution was swift – floods, slides, death felled the prideful. Out of each crisis and col- lapse the old people rose again and reestablished themselves. The most recent crisis, one that we have yet to find our way out of, was heralded in by the arrival of a new class of navigators: European merchant adven- tures. These sail powered ships arrived searching for new resources to exploit as part of the capitalist expansion out of Europe then underway. In addi- tion to being instrumental in expanding capitalist relations of production, these newcomers brought devastating disease that led to massive depopulation at genocidal levels. Out of the ensuing melee came the imposition of a system of economic and politi- Navigating the Way Toward Social Justice 6 • C. R. MENZIES cal governance that has prioritized greed, individual advancement, and dishonesty. The 20th century was witness to several disastrous attempts to find an escape from the depredations of capitalism and capitalists. The revolutionary attempts at change fell prey to the poisoned global environ- ment and crashed in on themselves. In their wake even worse examples of capitalist libertarianism have emerged. Mistakes can happen. Knowledge, tools, skills don’t guarantee that our journey is made without difficulty or mishap. I have stood in a wheelhouse of a boat when the seas were too rough, the condi- tions too dangerous to go forward. I recall one time when we were all gathered in the wheelhouse. We were heading out across a treacherous open body of water with the waves and wind coming up. A decision needed to be made. Did we keep moving forward, take the risk of that dangerous crossing? Ultimately the decision was made to turn back. Yet, even that decision was difficult to execute. To turn the boat at the wrong moment would capsize her. That I write about it nearly 40 years later testifies to the fact we made the turn and brought the boat around. The journey toward a more just society is fraught with turnarounds, disruptions, and even loss of faith in the possibility. The commentaries and arti- cles in the opening section of this issue hold fast to the idea that a better world is not only possible but also desirable. From scholarly activism to feminist interventions we have a set of tools and a body of knowledge that can help as we navigate forward. In the cracks and fissures of an imperfect capitalism we can make spaces for collaboration and cooperation, even in the center of imperialist nations (see Shannon this issue on museum collaborations with Indigenous curators). The papers in the second section of this issue provide additional content and analysis of the world that we must now navigate through. Here we see the role of information technology in shaping the early 21st century landscape of capitalism. A lot has changed since the days when a paper newspaper sold on a street corner could be a revolutionary instrument of change. Today the internet has superseded that older technology. Nonetheless the same configuration of capitalism remains at the heart of the problem: a patent disregard for human sentiment or dignity. We can offer no certainty about the outcome. We can and will offer examples to follow. Read on and join the journey toward social justice. work_dva4rxhtgbaahdymbvfbvoxgnq ---- Infinite Justice: An Architectural Coda Author(s): Arindam Dutta Source: Grey Room, No. 7, On 9/11 (Spring, 2002), pp. 40-55 Published by: The MIT Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1262584 Accessed: 28/05/2009 11:18 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=mitpress. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit organization founded in 1995 to build trusted digital archives for scholarship. We work with the scholarly community to preserve their work and the materials they rely upon, and to build a common research platform that promotes the discovery and use of these resources. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. The MIT Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Grey Room. http://www.jstor.org http://www.jstor.org/stable/1262584?origin=JSTOR-pdf http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=mitpress Infinite Justice: An Architectural Coda ARINDAM DUTTA We begin with Lyotard's opening paragraph on the "differend": As distinguished from a litigation, a differend [differend] would be a case of conflict, between (at least) two parties, that cannot be equitably resolved for lack of a rule of judgement applicable to both arguments. One side's legitimacy does not imply the other's lack of legitimacy. However, by applying a single rule of judgement to both in order to settle their differend as though it were merely a litigation would wrong (at least) one of them (and both of them if neither side admits this rule). Damages result from an injury which is inflicted upon the rules of a genre of discourse but which is reparable according to those rules. A wrong results from the fact that the rules of the genre of discourse by which one judges are not those of the judged genre or genres of discourse.1 There are the standard questions that need repeating: Whose justice? Whose history? Whose memory? Whose architecture? Whose modernity? Lyotard's dazzling passage introduces the concept of the differend as the residual or excess element in the scene of the encounter, any encounter, between heterogeneous modes of discourse. To be attentive to the differend is to bear witness to the irreducible alterity of the other, at the very point where either party seems to resist the very terms of the encounter. Lyotard opens the framing of the differend with a European example-the problem at hand is juridical, posed as a problem of evidence. Those who witnessed the gas chambers in action, those who could testify to their existence and use, died in them. In their absence, how are others to persuade the tribunals that the gas chambers did indeed exist, or more important, to whom do they owe justice when the victims themselves no longer live to phrase their tes- timony? Since the rest of the world did not die in the gas chambers, what world would be a beneficiary of this justice? The questions asked earlier can be reframed, not only as whose justice, but also as justice for whom? In its ultimate unwillingness to address these questions within its own territo- ries, Europe exports the "Jewish" differend to Asia. Let us reframe the differend through an Asian example. The place: Hopetown, part of the penal colony founded by the British in Grey Room 0 Spring 2002, pp. 40-55, 2002 Grey Room, Inc. and Massachusetts Institute of Technology 41 -~' 1' - . THE I1DIAN EMPIRE rpuea~ f Sir W3a? WImoa Wlsohmte MPERIAL GAZETTEER OF INDIA ,I. . ̂ &. L ::*n*r**rr u,~~~~ O "Map of India showing the Principal Buddhist Localities:' in James Fergusson: History of Indian and Eastern Architecture. (1876; Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal Publishers, 1998). 40 the Andaman and Nicobar islands, in the middle of the Bay of Bengal. The time: the evening of February 8,1872. A visiting dignitary, an Irishman named Richard Southwell Bourke steps off the boat along with his official retinue. They are here to inspect the programs set underway to "reform" the convicts. As they head back to the ship after having toured the island, a man creeps up behind Bourke, stabs him in the back, and kills him. The mur- derer's name, as far as we are able to determine, is Sher Ali. He is a Pashtun native of Jamrud, near Peshawar, at the foot of the Khyber Pass. After 1901, having miserably failed to conquer the entirety of the Pashtun homelands, the British will call this area the North-West Frontier Province (NWFP), a name that remains to the present day. Its strategic geopolitical importance as the frontier toward the vast Tsarist empire to the north takes precedence over local place names. To its immediate west is Afghanistan, much of whose population is composed of the same ethnic background as Sher Ali's. Over the period between 1838 and 1919, Britain and Russia will fight three major wars and many small battles in this region, using several local warlords as proxies and dupes. Sher Ali, a subaltern in the Peshawar police, had been arrested for avenging the murder of a kinsman by killing the assailant, a practice justified in tribal custom under certain conditions. British jurisprudence, which forbade the individual from taking the law into his own hands, deemed Ali's act a crim- inal infraction. The trial was carried out on what was at best questionable jurisdiction-had Ali incidentally carried out the murder outside of the porous borders of British-held territory, he would not have come under the purview of British law. Taking these circumstances into consideration, the magistrate handed out what he considered a lenient sentence-transporta- tion to the Andamans. It is precisely because of the importance given to cus- tom in British jurisprudence and political thought that the incarcerated subject has to be distanced from its "traditional" surroundings. Edmund Burke's traditionalism is as much the progenitor of the penal colony as the utilitarianism of Bentham. Considering this symbolic ignominy rather than legitimate punishment, Sher Ali asked to be put to death, rather than be incarcerated in a foreign land. This voluntary offer was, of course, ignored. At the Andamans, Ali now set about planning his own death, but this time he would factor in British imperial justice in an entirely new equation. When Sher Ali killed Bourke in 1872, he had waited four years for the opportunity, four years of planning and waiting not only for a significant victim to arrive but for his own death as well. And the murdered victim was the ideal one, indeed it was an assassination and not just a murder, since Bourke was none other than the Earl of Mayo, Benjamin Disraeli's appointee as the Viceroy of India, the Laat Saaheb2 of Britain's eastern empire. The 42 Grey Room 07 incident triggered shock waves across the world, including a corresponding burst of nationalism in Britain itself. Many commented on how mourning had "united" the country from its usual fractious internal rivalries. Newspapers opined and discussed, editorialized and investigated the possible geopolit- ical implications of the event. The British-run Friend of India suggested that the government "[s]end the scoundrel to perdition in a pig skin to break his caste."3 When asked to divulge his accomplices, Sher Ali refuted any larger plot, "Mera sharik koi ddmi nahin; merd sharfk khuda hai" (No mortal is my companion, my companion is God himself).4 His statement notwith- standing, almost everybody was intent on wrenching global meaning out of this isolated act. Liberals, nervous not to sound antipatriotic, made ineffec- tive noises attributing the act to disaffection over Britain's economic and taxation policies. Some pointed out Mayo's oppressive treatment of Wahhabism, an insurgent and millenarian movement that had recently emerged in India. The Times in London darkly hinted at the existence of a secret "fraternity of hatred," of a secret Wahhabi plot to undermine the British empire. Originally founded in the eighteenth century in the Nadj area where the Saud tribe had established a kingdom on its literalist emphasis on the reading of Islamic scriptures, the Wahhabi movement in India had no direct connections to the Arab context. Its beginnings stemmed from conversions to the cause in the eastern city of Patna. Its early campaigns had been directed against the Sikh kingdom, under which Muslims were badly off. Since the British were fight- ing the Sikhs at this time, they found it convenient to encourage them in the early stage. However, with the annexure of the Punjab in 1848, the Wahhabis increas- ingly became a thorn in the side of the colonial administration as well. After a spate of police crack-downs on the insurgent sect, tensions came to a head when J.P. Norman, the officiating Chief Justice of the Calcutta High Court, was assassinated on September 20, 1871 by a man affecting Wahhabi sym- pathies, barely three months before Mayo's own assassination. The specter of international insurgency with sectarian adherents as far distant as Mecca and Calcutta unnerved many who saw all manner of conspiracies being hatched to destabilize the British empire. It hardly helped that the Duke of Edinburgh, Victoria's second son, had been shot at by an Irish Fenian on the way from India to Australia in 1868.5 After Mayo's murder, officials searched for letters that Sher Ali might have received from the "Patna malcontents," hoping to establish links with the larger Wahhabi movement. No such "proof" was forthcoming. The British administration commemorated Mayo's short-lived career in India with a spate of institution building that would bring home the mes- sage of the intended persistence and tenacity of the Empire. Consequently, Dutta A Infinite Justice: A A rchitectural Cod 43 Left: Mayo School of Arts, now Pakistan's National College of Arts, Lahore. Photo: Arindam Dutta. Opposite, left: Lahore Museum, exterior. Although the museum as moved into this building after John Lockwood Kipling's departure from Lahore, it is a testimony to his legacy. Photo: Arindam Dutta. Opposite, right: Lahore Museum, interior. Photo: Arindam Dutta. even as the administration was unwilling to pub- licly state that Mayo was assassinated for political reasons, every official action they took thereafter reflected precisely those apprehensions. This Th-e o memorializing impetus realized its apogee in Lahore, capital of the erstwhile Sikh kingdom, i the latter a traditional enemy of the Afghan rulers, with the construction of the Lahore museum and the Mayo School of Art. Both the program and the form of these coupled institutions reflected the t . io transformed attitude of the administration toward .......accommodating "native agency" in the policies of governance, especially after the 1857 Mutiny. The spate of localized insurgencies that continued throughout the nine- teenth century was to keep the question of tradition alive in debates over colonial policy. In any case, the creation of the Punjab as a "nonregulatory" province in 1849 had already signaled the turn toward the institutionalization of native customary agency.6 This turn derived as much from economic considera- tions as political ones. A minimalist administration that left the terrain of domestic and personal law for native adjudication also absolved itself of the infrastructural costs of a full-fledged state apparatus at the periphery. From the mid-nineteenth century onward, colonialism seeks not so much to trans- form native subjecthood as to manage it. Punjab's administrative status thus contrasted sharply with the early "Regulatory" provinces (such as Bengal) where personal and domestic laws were brought directly under the purview of colonial jurisprudence. Recurrent insurgency from below owing to colonial interference in domestic and personal laws thus only appeared to justify a general tendency toward minimalism in colonial governance from above. This dual rationale was instrumental in shaping a decentralized and two- tiered policy where customary jurisprudence devolved to native authorities and the colonial administration retained control over political, criminal, and economic policy. Both feminist and other scholars of colonialism have noted that this two-tiered structure effectively exacerbated the patriarchal and despotic dimensions of this seemingly decentralized equation. In this system of "indirect" rule, traditional informal transactions acquired formal sanction from above, thus creating the conditions for increased native despotism at the ground level within the rubrics of "household," "caste," and "tribe." Imperialism resolves the problem of the differend by situating it within relativism. The architecture of colonialism reflected the above concerns of gover- nance at almost every level. The Mayo School and Museum were designed 44 on the lines of what was now shaping up to be the official architectural style of the British administration in India, the so-called Indo-Saracenic style. This representational motif was consistent with the general thrust of colo- nial policy in economic, political, and cultural fields. India would have her antiquity resurrected and restored to her through the recuperative stability of the Empire. To that effect, the manifestoes underlining the school and museum envisaged them as headquarters to document, incorporate and reinvigorate the traditional artisanal trades of the region in order to instill industriousness within native life. The sphere of "employment," realized through the alibi of traditional artisanry, could now be activated as a ruse to cover over the general economic depradation in the colonial landscape. In the imperial periphery, the monument is not so much a mute testimonial as a machine for subject formation.7 Let us cut to a scene within the Lahore Museum, which the British have renamed Jadoo-Ghar or Wonder House, appropriating native "irrationalist" colloquial language as official terminology.8 The time: indeterminate. We cannot be quite sure. The North-West is restive again. Beyond Afghanistan looms the vision of an all-pervasive Russian empire that threatens to infil- trate the core of Britain's territories in Asia. Soon there will be a war. At this time, a Tibetan lama arrives at the gates of the Museum. A boy playing out- side takes him in to meet the elderly curator, a white-bearded, gentle, learned Briton empathetically expert in the ways of the East. A peculiar encounter then unfolds-peculiar because it signals a shift in sign systems. The lama has come to the Museum because he has heard of the renowned Buddhist statuary kept there. At the sight of an image of Sakya Muni Buddha, the lama breaks down. The secularized ruins and fragmented museum display of a lost Buddhist civilization in South Asia suddenly becomes activated into a palpable and living idiom. Sculpture once again becomes idol. Curatorial Dutta It filnite Justice: An Architectural Coda 45 canon becomes religious pantheon. Seeming to acknowledge the East's greater profundity in these matters, the European curator defers his sense of ratio- nalist historiography to the lama's transcendentalist understanding. Both the curator and the lama, through their respective powers of knowledge and faith, appear to share a stupendous secret that both must realize in their sep- arate ways. "We be craftsmen together, thou and I," the lama tells the cura- tor, in their respective quest for a redemptive destiny. The history of the past encapsulated in these lifeless images augurs a future British India where knowledge and religion will impeccably coincide in a time of peace to come. As proxy agent for the curator's epistemological project, Kim, the little brown-skinned boy loitering outside the museum will accompany the lama on his sacred search in order to realize this convergent prophecy. The scene is, of course, from Rudyard Kipling's Kim.9 It is well known that Kipling based the character of the curator on his father, John Lockwood Kipling, professor of architectural ornament, founding principal and cura- tor of the Mayo School and the Lahore Museum. Part of an emergent gener- ation of liberal colonial administrators, Kipling Sr. derived his creed from the ongoing scholarly effort by the British to unravel the native's frame of action and ethics through the extraordinary interdisciplinary collaboration between quite distinct professional endeavors. Colonial scholars such as James Fergusson (in significant ways the doyen of a global architectural history) and, in his wake, Alexander Cunningham, first head of the Archaeological Survey of India, equated formal typologies with different ethnic and racial groupings.10 Thus Indian architectural history came to be periodized into successive stages such as "Buddhist," "Jain," "Brahmanical," "Indo-Scythian," "Pathan," or "Moghul," respectively.11 The institution of the Archaeological Survey underlined a series of parallel initiatives in museology and preser- vation. At least part of the concern over colonial archaeology and preservation stemmed from the fact that Indians themselves seemed to be least interested in either recovering or preserving their own past. Under a recuperative imperial epistemology, the contemporary Indian (or for that matter, Greek or Egyptian) unable to gauge his sense of historical agency, would gain a sense of his ethical present through the colonialist excavation of the past. Memory must be instituted as if intuited. We are in Blade Runner territory here-historical memory is always already an implant. This is the secret, the fabulous normalization of complicity between colonizer and colonized, that is shared by the curator and the lama-the curator desires to institute what the lama intuits. The lama's character is also significant for another reason. As is well known, the overwhelming and minuscule minority of Europeans as compared with the native population necessitated the creation of a native gentry and 46 Grey Room 07 bourgeoisie who would act as imperialism's agents at the periphery. It is the native bourgeoisie's political consciousness, ever susceptible to European notions of political action and opposition, that must be circumscribed by this form of history. In Kim, the Bengali Hindu spy for the British and aspi- rant to membership of the Royal Geographical Society, Hurree [Hari] Babu, the figure held most in contempt by Kipling-approximates the subjective outlines of this emergent figure.12 In the affairs of British India, Buddhism, more or less a political nonentity, could therefore also be invoked as a major alibi in the establishment of Pax Britannica, precisely to counter this polit- ically emergent subject (both Hindu and Muslim) militantly recuperating its religious identity as instrument for sedition. With the transition of mercantilism to industrial capitalism in Europe, transcoded in philosophy and culture as the "Enlightenment," European states could dissemble their identity as triumph of the political state over religion. However, the basic identification of every European state with one particular religion remains to this day a dirty little secret that could be made visible, or covered over at will. In this sense, there is nothing "spontaneous" about singing "God Bless America" on the Capitol steps in Washington. Triumphal religion can write this history quite differently: the massacre of Jews in Europe could be written off as a crime of the German nation rather than a crime of Christianity. This is not restricted to the First World. At the height of the first wave of secular nationalisms in the Third World, to the astonishment of many, "religion" was introduced as one of the two funda- mental principles to be discussed at the famed Bandung conference in 1955.13 In a classic instance of derivative postcoloniality, Third World lead- ers pledged to build solidarity in the shared fight against underdevelopment and European colonialism on the principles of Buddhism.14 In the nineteenth century it is because of this fear of an insurgent nation- alism driven by religion that imperialist politics acquires its secular face in the global arena. The secularism of European polity would be used not to battle religion in Europe, but to circumscribe it in the colony. Religion would therefore both be undone in its insurgent potentials, even as some of its ele- ments would be transcendentalized into proxy ideologies for the imperial agenda of keeping the peace. The political script of empire could now be read as our Benjamin Disraeli, your Gautama Buddha. Through this political reframing of the economic theater of imperialism as a cultural conundrum, as a conflict between religion and customs, the colonized native bourgeoisie would be pried away from attending to the most depredatory effects of the British imperial system. The skeletons of the 30 million Indian dead from starvation in the period between 1870 to 1947 would be covered over by the bourgeois staging of a conflict between cultures and civilizations.15 Dutta i tnfinite Justice: An Architectural Coda 47 In the context of colonial archaeology, the contending claims of a cultur- alist ethnography invoking an identification between native agency and the romantic evocation of place found itself at odds with the demands of scien- tific epistemology and research. The claims of the museum, repository of the latter strategy and of the Enlightenment principles of disinterested study of objects removed from their context, began to be squared off in the 1860s against the countervailing principle of preserving artifacts and buildings in situ. Even as the introduction of reproductive techniques such as photogra- phy, casts, and drawings appeared to satisfy museumatic demands, colonial archaeologists and architectural historians now saw India itself as an open- air museum. The categories created in the museum were now extended to the geographical map itself. Henry Hardy Cole, first Curator of the Department of the Conservation of Ancient Monuments, founded in 1880, therefore reclassified the Indian map, marking different sites as B (Buddhist), H (Hindu), J (Jain), or M (Muhammadan). Imperialism places the differend within relativism-but this relativism is limned precisely byfiguring a tran- scendentalist identity larger than the peoples that encompass it. In the con- text of the Indian North-West the largely neofeudal character of the colonial administration, born out of political expediency, is supplemented by parallel claims to the transcendant history of Islam and Buddhism in the region. Thus, the many "open-air" sites of the Gandhara region and the Bamiyan Buddhas complement the limited institutional locus of the Lahore and the nearby Kabul museum-thus explicitly encoding them within a larger regional identity that appears to figure its importance in global civilization. It is important to note here that this dyad of regional trans-signification and global particularity is the principal thematic invoked in the first wave of anticolonial nationalist imaginaries. It is because of the noncoincidence of transcendentalist imagination and geographical map that the nationalist project can be said to be a kind of longing for an origin that is inevitably located "elsewhere." Nothing epitomizes this better than the case of the two states carved out of British India. The Indus Valley civilization, perceived fount of Indian history, has most of its archaeological remains located inside Pakistan, while the principal imperial remains of Pakistan's presumed cul- tural forbearers, the Islamic emperors, are located inside India. In the after- math of so-called political decolonization, the complicity between this flawed transregional imaginary and a derivative Eurocentrism can be said to be underpinned by the creation of the United Nations, the old cosmopolitan specter of a global community of nation-states. Correspondingly, institu- tions such as UNESCO and the World Heritage project can be considered to be the direct legatees of the Fergussons and the Cunninghams in that their prin- cipal aim is more to secure a global pax than to sanctify local imaginaries. 48 In contemporary South Asia this has had some interesting ramifications. On December 6, 1992, gangs of the Hindu religious right destroyed an aban- doned mosque, the Babri Masjid, named after the first Mughal emperor Babar, in the northern Indian town of Ayodhya. Even as this symbolic affront cre- ated ripples across Asia and the Islamic world, the mavens of Eurocentric global "cosmopolitanism" and agencies such as UNESCO kept quiet. The destruction of a mundane mosque was an affair too regional to be of import to the concept of World Heritage. In the subsequent national election, the political party responsible for the destruction was voted into power in India's federal government. It remains there today. In the beginning of 2001 the Taliban government, enraged at what it perceived as the global commu- nity's apathy toward its economic desperation, blew up the ancient Buddhist sculptures in the province of Bamiyan. B becomes M on the map. The spark appears to have been ignited by UNESCO's offer to come in with teams and millions of dollars to preserve the sculptures when the Taliban was desperately seeking international funding to stabilize its government. Militia leaders also pointed to the destruction of the Babri Masjid as precedent. The "international community's" reaction was distinctly different from the Babri Masjid incident. In the context of the history that I have narrated above, how are we to read these apparently corresponding acts of iconoclasm? Identitarian funda- mentalism against capitalist cosmopolitanism? As comeuppance for a his- toriographic strategy set in place by imperialism? As the revenge of the local and particular against the global and the universal? Not quite. First of all, under the dispensations of modernity realized by imperialism and neocolonialism, the global can hardly be equated with the universal. Conversely, the local is hardly the particular. I would like to return us to the concept of the differend, and with it the singular case, both juridical and historiographic, of Sher Ali. I have noted above that he had requested to be executed by the British administration rather than be trans- ported to a distant place. In the following section I will attempt to suggest that Ali's request can be said to be unraveling the project of European humanism. There are a few more determinants that one would have to con- sider along the way. One question cannot be ignored, especially after close to two hundred years of a repetitive history-Why Afghanistan? Peter Hopkirk's extraordi- nary series of books on Central Asia have highlighted the incredible history of the contestations over the region by the great imperial powers. Of these books, written from an Anglophone romantic perspective, The Great Game: On Secret Service in High Asia is remarkable. In addition, five of his other books also narrate the complicity between imperial geopolitics and humanist knowledge gathering in this region. These are: Trespassers on the Roof of the 49 World, Setting the East Ablaze, Foreign Devils on the Silk Road, Questfor Kim, and Like Hidden Fire.16 Reading these books not entirely against their grain, I would like to expli- cate the question "Why Afghanistan?" through Louis Althusser's invocation of the Leninist theme of "the weakest link": "A chain is as strong as its weakest link."17 In the aftermath of the October revolution, Lenin attempted to theo- rize its inexplicable early triumph by asking the question "Why Russia?" Lenin calculated that the overwhelming contradictions articulated in Russian society, the overlap of advanced industrialism in the cities and exacerbated feudalism in the rural areas, the crepuscular "ignorance" of the peasantry, and the enlightened cosmopolitanism of its exiled political elites derived as much from internal determinants as from its external relationship with regard to the other imperialist states. Given the particular stage of global his- tory in the aftermath of the war, "Russia was the weakest link in the chain of the imperialist states."18 While it is these contradictions that fuel the rev- olution, in its aftermath it became clear that the bourgeois revolution could not be coincided with the peasant revolution. It goes without saying there- fore that Stalin sought to sew up these maximized contradictions through the vision of a bourgeois "Communist Party that was a chain without weak links."19 The contradictions were erased rather than worked through. With this frame in mind, I would like to suggest Afghanistan's status as a "weak link" in the chain of colonized states. Its locus is defined by maximum overdetermination in the context of Eurocentric imperialist geopolitics and maximum undermining of the project of Eurocentric modernity. Suspended in the cusp, the no-man's-land and buffer state between two superpowers, it was therefore the global nonplace that not only was not colonized, but could not be colonized.20 The global "balance of powers" figures the national ter- ritory of Afghanistan as absence-the Taliban's effort to secure national integrity is therefore as much a Stalinist eradication of weak links as an instance of theocratic oligarchy. In September 1996 one of the first acts of retribution by the Taliban after the conquest of Kabul was the execution of Najibullah, former head of the genocidal secret service agency Khad, and Communist president during the Soviet era. Before he was dragged out from the U.N. compound, where he had sought refuge after the defeat of his government by U.S.-backed Islamist rebels in 1992, Najibullah had told U.N. officials that he was translating Peter Hopkirk's The Great Game into Pashto.21 This last ditch, and failed, attempt to institute for Afghans the narrative of the overdetermination of Afghanistan's modern history exemplifies its failed nationalism. I have tangentially indicated earlier that it became the lot of the great anticolonialist nationalisms to undo the imperialist legacy of neofeudalism 50 Grey Room 07 and transcendentalist religion in the colony. In Western Europe, the vaunted "democratic" revolutions of the modern era-the nominal accession of the representative population of the nation-state into political rights-could only proceed as a stage-bound maneuver. At each stage a newly emergent class gaining access to political representation prepared the ground for the next, so that the classes below the current dispensation could only enter this ambit to the extent that they acceded to the key ideological motifs of the rul- ing class. It must be pointed out that the great decolonization struggles-in the Third World, in their embrace of the nation-state as liberative instru- ment-set out to achieve this historical transformation at the single stroke of an hour. This caprice presaged their failure-both from within and without. In today's neocolonial context, Afghanistan is not the only place in the world where this project can be said to be failing.22 If the bourgeois-communist Najibullah waited for his death by unsuc- cessfully attempting to forge a nationalist, therefore modern, historiography, Sher Ali's wait for death marks the failed relationship to modernity in a slightly different way. As a Pashtun, Sher Ali's linguistic-ethnic matrix is split between imperial extraterritoriality (Afghanistan) and the terra firma of British justice (NWFP). It is here that his case can be seen to approxi- mate the differend between neofeudalism and the enlightenment subject. In his dying confession, Sher Ali stated that the slaying of a hereditary foe was no crime in his eyes. In spite of this disavowal of culpability, however, he preferred to be executed rather than be transported and kept alive. Operative in this is a robust sense of submission to justice, even when jus- tice is delivered through the law of the other. On the other hand, the British magistrate's decision to transport him cannot be seen as anything less than a humane act. Embedded in this act is the exemplary tolerance of British liberal humanism toward the nuances of customary and common law. And yet, for Sher Ali, the core of the injustice lies in the decision to keep him alive rather than kill him. On the level of singular acts of justice, this asymp- tote epitomizes the differend-the honorability of either side cannot be doubted at the level of singular intention. Two systems of justice seek to compete not by undoing but by outdoing the other. However, in his next crime, the murder of the Viceroy, Sher Ali puts this very singularity, and therefore this presumed honorability of intent, into question. European liberal humanism could unfold as a global ethic only under the cocked rifle hammer of British imperialism. Sher Ali's lunge with the knife undoes this coerced complicity-it is here that his revolt becomes systemic, the unraveling of a protocol of power, rather than merely an intu- itive opposition. It is important to note here that Islam acts as customary constraint rather than messianic injunction. Dua nfinite Justice: An Architectural Coda 51 This reading is further intensified by his response to a telegram sent by Mayo's children on the eve of his execution. On hearing their message, "May God forgive you," Ali became enraged, saying that if they had sent a message ordering him to be cut to pieces he would have been glad, but a prayer for God's forgiveness he could not accept from them.23 I grant you the right to punish, but not the right to forgive. I accept your law, but not your justice. It is because the origins of modernity in the colony are inexplicably tied up with the ends of imperialism that its outlines operate as a historical tele- ology in reverse: first the institution of the neofeudal-capitalist/disciplinary apparatus (even within the postcolonial "independent" state), while the "enlightenment" of the native is a project that can be deferred endlessly. But the assassin or the insurgent are more functions of discursive difference- the activators of the differend-than they are representations of a "non- modern" native will or symptoms of some "other" manner of being. It is the teleology of imperial discourse itself that is unraveled by the assassin. Sher Ali's action produces a crisis at the geopolitical level. At the same time his narrative singularity can neither be embraced by statist historiog- raphy (whether imperialist or Third World nationalist) nor can it be approx- imated to modes of collective "political" insurgency. Sher Ali's ethical trajectory is in the great apocalyptic master narratives of modernity, but not ofthem. Within the province of law, Lyotard points out that the "humanist" assumption of innocence on the part of the accused primarily benefited hegemonic power, since its victims could never formulate their testimony into a cognizable "phrase."24 Sher Ali's singular narrative cannot therefore be recognized by colonial power as full-fledged "political" consciousness. This is why in the first historiographic account we encounter of his story, Mayo's biography, his name is willfully written out: "Neither his name, nor that of his village or tribe, will find record in this book."25 The early Subaltern Studies collective in India read the colonial archive to tease out precisely such irruptions in its textual protocols. In the colonial records of anticolonial insurgency, subalternist historians saw these insurgencies as necessarily failing (since colonial power could always muster enough force to stamp them out physically) and yet leaving their trace as a crisis in the textuality of colonial historiography.26 Sher Ali's plea inviting his own execution reveals death itself as the keeper of the differend. If I cannot live according to my norms in your (triumphal- ist) juridical frame, then let me die so that the norm can be preserved. Bury the differend so that it can be mourned "properly." Do not rationalize it away and leave it to fester as the province of the irrational. Humanistic justice, willfully noncognizant of its complicity with imperialism, cannot honor this plea as a desire for modernity, a plea for accession to a universal justice, a 52 justice that could also be the name for a modernity yet to come-a moder- nity and a justice that the Christianized pax imperialis can never bear. Unlike Western Europe, internal revolutions-the necessary "working through" that leads the ancestors to their proper burial-continue to be interdicted across the (neo)colonial world. The differend must invoke other forms to win recognition. 53 Notes This paper has benefited immensely from my conversations with Kryzstof Wodiczko. I am grateful for his input. 1. Jean-Francois Lyotard, The Differend: Phrases in Dispute (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1988), xi. 2. Colloquial expression for "Lord Sahib," the administration's own vernacularist term for the viceregal position. 3. The politics of religion in British colonial sociology was yet to unfurl in its formal dimensions. 4. William Wilson Hunter, Rulers of India: The Earl of Mayo (London: Oxford Clarendon Press, 1891), 198. 5. Mayo himself had served as Chief Secretary for Ireland back in Britain, the experience from which was considered a positive attribute in being appointed Viceroy of India. 6. See John Stuart Mill's comments on the subject in Mill, Writings on India, Vol. XXX of the Collected Works (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1990), 116. 7. See Arindam Dutta, Designing the Present: The Cole Circle and the Architecture of (an) Imperial Bureaucracy (Ph.D. diss., Princeton University, 2001). 8. See Dutta, ch. 5, "Peasants in the Architecture: Event and the Politics of Representation." 9. Rudyard Kipling, Kim (New York: Penguin Books, 1997). 10. See Tapati Guha-Thakurta, "The Museumised Relic: Archaeology and the First Museum of Colonial India," The Indian Economic and Social History Review 34, no. 1: 21-51. My account of the politics of the Archaeological Survey of India derives substantially from her analysis. 11. Developing from its own roots in a monarchical system, British colonialist historiog- raphy (as opposed to French, for example) developed an account of India's past as riven by internecine conflict between feudal and kingly states, alternating with periods of stability and prosperity realized only at periods of comprehensive imperial consolidation. Two such sanctified periods, the widespread empires of the Hindu (and later Buddhist) king Ashoka and the Mughal emperor Akbar, thus reflected not only what the British saw as the two prin- cipal religious constituencies in their Indian empire, but also seemed to presage the institu- tion of Victoria as Empress of India in 1877. 12. I thought of Hurree Babu as we saw the recent televised images of the Northern Alliance, ridiculously costumed in jungle warfare fatigues in a patently arid and desert landscape. After the fall of Kabul, news reports reach us of these mimic soldiers dragging women out of their houses and ripping off their burqas in front of Western cameramen and journalists, thus claiming to have "liberated" them. 13. Albert Memmi notes this with not little consternation in the aftermath of the Algerian revolution. Albert Memmi, The Colonizer and the Colonized (Boston: Beacon Press, 1965), 133. 14. Mike Mason, Development and Disorder: A History of the Third World since 1945 (Hanover: University Press of New England, 1997), 31. 15. That starvation-based genocide across the world under British imperialism was an unintended effect of its economic policies made it no less a planned event. See Mike Davis, Late Victorian Holocausts: El Nino Famines and the Making of the Third World (London: Verso, 2001). 16. Peter Hopkirk, The Great Game: On Secret Service in High Asia (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991); Foreign Devils on the Silk Road: The Search for the Lost Trea.sures 54 Grey Room 07 of Central Asia (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980); Trespassers on the Roof of the World: The Race for Lhasa (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1982); Setting the East Ablaze: On Secret Service in BolshevikAsia (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984); Questfor Kim: In Search of Kipling's Great Game (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1996); and Like Hidden Fire: The Plot to Bring Down the British Empire (New York: Kodansha International, 1997). 17. Louis Althusser, "Contradiction and Overdetermination," in For Marx, trans. Ben Brewster (London: Verso, 1969). 18. Althusser, 97. 19. Althusser, 98. 20. The Balkan states play out a comparable thematic on the European side-except that their proximities to the countries of the Enlightenment locate them within the crisis of "Europe" as cosmopolitan superstate. 21. New York Times, 6 October 1996. "Afghanistan Reels Back into View," cited in Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak, "Foucault and Najibullah," in OtherAsias (Oxford: Blackwell, forthcoming). 22. The Indian economist Prabhat Patnaik's work on the fiscal legacies of the older terri- torial imperialism in today's decentralized neocolonialism, and their relationship to the resurgence of antidemocratic authoritarianism in the South, is illuminating here, especially in the context of macroeconomic "conditionalities" imposed by the World Bank/International Monetary Fund/WTO triad. Prabhat Patnaik, "Whatever Happened to Imperialism?" in Whatever Happened to Imperialism and Other Essays (New Delhi: Tulika Press, 1995), 209-210. 23. George Pottinger, Mayo: Disraeli's Viceroy (Salisbury: Michael Russell, 1990), 188. 24. When sufficiently challenged, hegemonic power can transform itself into despotic power and suspend this assumption of innocence-vengeance can overrule other principles of justice. 25. W.W. Hunter: A Life of the Earl of Mayo, Vol. II (London: Smith, Elder and Co., 1876), 366. 26. See Ranajit Guha, "The Prose of Counter-Insurgency," in Subaltern Studies II: Writings on South Asian History and Society (New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1983), 1-42. Dutta I Infinite Justice: An Architectural Coda 55 Article Contents p. 41 p. 40 p. 42 p. 43 p. 44 p. 45 p. 46 p. 47 p. 48 p. 49 p. 50 p. 51 p. 52 p. 53 p. 54 p. 55 Issue Table of Contents Grey Room, No. 7, On 9/11 (Spring, 2002), pp. 1-158 Front Matter [pp. 1-5] The Editors [pp. 6-7] Twin Memories: Afterimages of Nine/Eleven [pp. 8-13] War, Terrorism, and Spectacle, or: On Towers and Caves [pp. 14-23] Terrorism, Feminism, Sisters, and Twins: Building Relations in the Wake of the World Trade Center Attacks [pp. 24-39] Infinite Justice: An Architectural Coda [pp. 40-55] Explanation and Exoneration, or What We Can Hear [pp. 56-67] The Language of Damage [pp. 68-71] Dangerous Fragments [pp. 72-81] A City Transformed: Designing 'Defensible Space' [pp. 82-85] Divided Responsibilities: Minoru Yamasaki, Architectural Authorship, and the World Trade Center [pp. 86-95] Around Ground Zero [pp. 96-101] City Square: Structural Engineering, Democracy and Architecture [pp. 102-105] Enduring Innocence [pp. 106-113] One or More [pp. 114-123] Building Global Modernisms [pp. 124-134] Editor's Note [p. 135] "Welcome to Crisis!": Notes for a Pictorial History of the Pictorial Histories of the Arab Israeli War of June 1967 [pp. 136-158] Back Matter work_dvsmveuqovdljicvwpqrevd72e ---- POLIS. Volume 15. Issues 1 and 2, 1998 SOCIAL JUSTICE IN PLATO�S REPUBLIC Robert Heinaman In two papers on the Republic1 Gregory Vlastos argued that, insofar as it con- cerns the distribution of goods or �the allocation of substantive rights,�2 social justice was determined for Plato by �the Principle of Functional Reciprocity�: (FR) All members of the polis have equal right to those and only those benefits which are required for the optimal performance of their function in the polis.3 As everyone knows, Plato�s ideal state divides into three classes � produc- ers, auxiliaries and guardians � which perform different roles to promote the city�s wellbeing. Producers furnish the material necessities of life, auxiliaries form an army to protect the city from external and internal enemies, and guardians rule. According to FR, one�s rights are determined by the class to which one is assigned and by one�s specific task within that class: provided that one actually performs one�s function or work,4 one receives whatever 1 �The Theory of Social Justice in the Polis in Plato�s Republic�, Studies in Greek Philosophy II (Princeton, 1995), pp. 69�103; originally printed in Helen North, ed., Interpretations of Plato (Leiden, 1977) (Mnemosyne, Suppl. vol. 50), pp. 1�40; �The Rights of Persons in Plato�s Conception of the Foundation of Justice�, Studies in Greek Philosophy II, pp. 104�25; originally published in H. Tristram Englehardt, Jr., and Daniel Callahan, eds., Morals, Science and Society (Hastings-on-Hudson, N.Y., 1978), pp. 172�201. All page references are to the articles as published in Studies in Greek Philosophy II. 2 �Social Justice�, p. 86. 3 �Rights of Persons�, p. 110. 4 �Rights of Persons�, pp. 112, 123. In FR �one�s work� refers solely to one�s spe- cific task or role, such as shoemaking or cobbling. But Vlastos allows that the phrase can also refer to the entire range of public and private obligations governing one�s conduct, and many of these obligations are not tied to one specific job such as shoe- making (�Social Justice�, p. 79): �this �single service in the polis� [�doing one�s own�], though vocationally based, is not meant to be restricted to on-the-job activity but to extend over the whole of one�s conduct in the polis, private no less than public.� Vlastos is correct to recognize this broad use of �doing one�s own�, and hence of �justice.� (See, for example, 441d�e and 443a). But he does not appear to realize that this recognition conflicts with his previously argued claim that in the Republic δικαιοσβνη is restricted to the narrow use of the term (�Social Justice�, pp. 73�78). If justice is �doing one�s work� and �one�s work� refers to �the whole of one�s conduct 24 R. HEINAMAN goods one needs in order to carry out one�s job. One receives no other goods and, in particular, one is denied anything that might damage one�s ability to perform one�s job as well as possible. At the same time, Vlastos argued against the view that social justice in the Republic is based on proportional equality, the account of justice which in ancient times was set out most fully by Aristotle. According to proportional equality,5 justice exists when goods are distributed to people in proportion to their merit or desert (¢x�a). In the simplest case involving two people � A and B � justice exists when the ratio of the value of the good assigned to A to the value of the good assigned to B equals the ratio of the merit of A to the merit of B � The merit of A The value of the goods assigned to A ------------------- = --------------------------------------------- The merit of B The value of the good assigned to B. Clearly, this idea of proportional equality is very general and loose, and as stated so far it is compatible with all sorts of views about distributive justice, depending on how we identify the goods to be distributed, their value, and the merit of the people who receive them. Thus, when Aristotle discusses the just distribution of political power, he refers to disagreements about what the relevant merit is which validates its possession.6 Democrats maintain that what determines a person�s merit is being a free citizen, and therefore, since all free citizens equally share this merit, all deserve an equal amount of po- litical power. Since all free citizens cannot occupy political office at the same time, office holding is settled by lot. Oligarchs, on the other hand, maintain that political power should be distributed on the basis of the possession of a certain degree of wealth, while aristocrats maintain that it is virtue which warrants the possession of political power.7 According to Vlastos, when considering the Republic�s account of politi- cal justice we should forget all about proportional equality.8 I believe that this is a mistake and that proportional equality plays an important role in the Re- in the polis�, then this must be justice in the broad use which is identical with virtue as a whole. 5 For a good exposition of Aristotle�s position, see D. Keyt, �Aristotle�s Theory of Distributive Justice�, in D. Keyt and F. Miller, Jr. (eds.), A Companion to Aristotle's Politics (Oxford, 1991), pp. 240�47. 6 NE 1131a24�29; cf. Pol. 1280a18�19, 1282b14�23. Aristotle also claims that people agree about the value of the goods distributed (Pol. 1280a18�19). 7Cf. Rep. 549a, 550c�d 551a�b, 557a, 558c, 562b�c. 8 �Social Justice�, p. 89. SOCIAL JUSTICE IN PLATO�S REPUBLIC 25 public�s account of social justice.9 The first part of my paper will try to show that Vlastos� arguments against so interpreting the Republic are not convinc- ing. I do not claim that Vlastos is wrong to think that a principle along the lines of FR plays an important role in the Republic. Rather, I believe that Vlastos failed to see how easily the idea behind his principle could be ab- sorbed by the notion of proportional equality. Furthermore, while this idea behind FR plays a significant part in Plato�s account of justice, it is insuffi- cient as a full account of social justice in the Republic because, as I will argue in the second part of the paper, there are several important decisions which Plato makes about the distribution of goods which FR cannot explain. On the other hand, these decisions can be explained on the basis of proportional equality. I Vlastos� position is based on the contention that Plato makes certain choices about the distribution of goods in the city which conflict with the distribution required by proportional equality. He makes four points which I will consider in turn. (1) Vlastos says that, apart from the distribution of honour, �Platonic jus- tice would flout �proportional� equality . . . � by giving less of some of the major means of happiness to those who give the polis more�.10 By �the major means of happiness� Vlastos means a normal sexual and family life, and pri- vate property. These are denied the guardians � �those who give the polis more� � on the grounds that such goods would undermine the guardians� ability to rule the city properly. Here Vlastos takes the fact that the guardians do not get certain goods to show that they are not distributed on the basis of proportional equality. Therefore, he must be assuming that the guardians would merit or deserve these goods according to proportional equality. And so he is assuming that 9 Vlastos (�Social Justice�, p. 87, n. 84) refers to the following authors as holding that proportional equality is upheld in the Republic: E. Barker, Greek Political Theory (New York, 1951), p. 139, n. 2; K. Bringmann, Studien zu den politischen Ideen des Isokrates (Hypomnemata, no. 14, 1965), p. 86; R. Maurer, Platons �Staat� und die Demokratie (Berlin, 1970), p. 75f. I have not been able to obtain Bringmann�s book. See also E. Barker, The Political Thought of Plato and Aristotle (New York, 1959), p. 20, n. 1; J. Derbalov, �Ursprungsmotive und Prinzipien der Platonischen Staatsden- kens�, Kantstudien, 55 (1964), pp. 274�76, 290. Cf. also M.B. Foster, �On Plato�s Conception of Justice in the Republic�, Philosophical Quarterly, 1 (1951/52), p. 209. 10 �Social Justice�, pp. 88�89. There is some unclarity about what Vlastos believes determines merit according to proportional equality. In the passage under discussion he assumes that proportional equality would say that one merits or deserves goods in proportion to one�s degree of contribution to the good of the city. But he also assumes that it would say that the basis for deciding one�s merit is one�s degree of virtue (p. 89). 26 R. HEINAMAN proportional equality is committed to the following: what one deserves is de- termined by what contribution one makes to the wellbeing of the city, and what one�s contribution to the wellbeing of the city entitles one to is all so- cially distributable goods in proportion to the scale of one�s contributions. One problem here is Vlastos� assumption that Plato regards the items in question as among �the major means of happiness.� Plato, of all people, does not set a high value on possessions;11 nor does the Republic12 or the Sympo- sium suggest that he regards a family or sexual relations as among �the major means of happiness.� In his opinion, the guardians are given the best life pos- sible, and the belief that the items in question are necessary for happiness is dismissed as �a foolish adolescent opinion about happiness� (Republic 465d- 466b). Since Plato rejects Vlastos� assumption, even if proportional equality said that �the major means of happiness� should be distributed in proportion to people�s contribution to the wellbeing of the city, it would not imply that the guardians should receive more of the goods in question than anyone else. So the fact that Plato does not allow such items to be distributed to the guardians would not show that distributive justice in the Republic is not de- termined by proportional equality. More seriously, Vlastos� argument rests on a misunderstanding of the idea of proportional equality, for that idea can easily assimilate the point behind FR and explain Plato�s decision about the distribution of the goods which Vlastos says are among �the major means of happiness�. Proportional equality does not say that people should receive all goods to that degree which matches their degree of virtue. Nor does it say that people should receive all goods to that degree which matches their contribution to the city�s wellbeing. Proportional equality can allow that �what people merit� will be determined by different factors in different cases, depending on what good is being distributed and for what purpose. There is no reason why the question of how the possession of a good would affect one�s ability to per- form one�s function may not be among the considerations which determine what one merits when certain goods are distributed. Thus, in the Laws (744b- c), where justice is explained in terms of proportional equality (756e-758a), Plato points out that it is not virtue alone which determines the merit (¢x�a) that grounds the distribution of burdens and benefits according to propor- tional equality. Vlastos seems to be making a mistake which Aristotle criticizes when ex- plaining his view of social justice, viz. the mistake that results when people think that if they are equal (or unequal) in one respect, they are equal (or un- equal) in all.13 Aristotle discusses an example where the question is how to distribute justly a limited number of flutes. He does not think that the flutes should be distributed to those who have the greatest virtue of character or to 11 Cf. Rep. 485d�e, 491c, 493d, 495a, 547b, 559b�c. 12 Rep. 395d�e, 402e�403c, 485d�e. 13 Pol. 1280a21�25; cf. 1282b18�30, 1283a26�27, and Rep. 551b�d. SOCIAL JUSTICE IN PLATO�S REPUBLIC 27 those who have contributed most to the wellbeing of the polis, or to those who are better born or more beautiful. Among fluteplayers who are equal in the art we should not give the prefer- ence of flutes to the more nobly born, because they will not play any better. We should give the superiority in instruments to him who is superior at the work (�rgon) . . . If someone excelled at playing the flute, but was very in- ferior in birth or beauty, then, even if each of these is a greater good than fluteplaying (I mean birth and beauty), and even if their superiority to fluteplaying is proportionately greater than his superiority as a fluteplayer, still he should be given the outstanding flutes. For their superiority must contribute to the work (�rgon); but superiority in wealth and birth contrib- ute nothing.14 For Aristotle, proportional equality maintains that what determines merit in specific cases will depend on what good is being distributed, and on the pur- pose for the sake of which it is being distributed.15 So if flutes are being distributed for the purpose of organizing an orchestra to play music as well as possible, then merit is determined by flute playing skill, by who can do the work that accomplishes the end in view. As far as the distribution of this good for this purpose goes, it does not matter how virtuous or vicious those with flute playing skill may be. Plato makes a similar point in the Republic (453d�455a) when he is con- sidering how to distribute functions or tasks, and starts to justify his belief that women should be assigned the same jobs as men. Earlier,16 Socrates had said that for justice to be realized in the city, people with different natures (ϕÚσεις) should be assigned different functions: justice will be realized when people do their own work according to nature (453b). Since men and women differ in nature, the proposal for women to be given the same jobs as men might appear to contradict the earlier rule on the assignment of tasks. Plato now points out that the contradiction is only apparent. In saying that different natures should be assigned different jobs, he did not mean that if our present 14 Pol. 1282b33�1283a3. Richard Robinson�s translation. 15 Cf. Pol. 1280a25�36, and III.9 as a whole, where the determination of political justice rests on determining what a polis is, which depends on determining the end of the polis. According to Aristotle, it is the fact that what determines merit depends on the purpose of the community in question which is �the main point� (1280a25) missed by those who think that if they are equal in one respect they are equal in all, and by those who think that if they are unequal in one respect they are unequal in all (1280a16�24). As NE 1160a8�25 shows, the purpose is closely tied to the kind of association (koinwn�a) between people that is in question. And in at least many cases, what people merit depends on what relations exist between the associated parties. For example, in the association of a father with a son, or a husband with a wife, �the justice . . . that exists between persons so related is not the same on both sides but is in every case proportional to merit� (NE 1161a21�22; cf. IX.2). 16 Rep. 412b�415b. 28 R. HEINAMAN day shoemakers are bald-headed, then hairy men should be banned from shoemaking on the grounds that they differ in nature. Although they do, in a way, differ in nature, it is not a difference that is relevant to the question of who should be a shoemaker. People are alike and different in various respects, and in assigning jobs we must specify what difference in nature is relevant. This is done, Plato says, by making it clear what it is with reference to which natures are to be distin- guished; and this determining factor is the task to be performed.17 If we must look to the purpose for the sake of which an item is being distributed, then just as beauty is irrelevant in deciding who should be given flutes, so degree of hairiness is irrelevant in deciding who ought to be a shoemaker or a sol- dier. The items in question should be distributed to those with the relevant ability for performing the task in question. Since difference in sex does not necessarily affect the capacity to perform the jobs to be done in the city, i.e. does not affect one�s �nature� in the relevant sense, women will often merit the same jobs as men.18 The view that the just distribution of goods to people depends on the �na- tures� of the recipients is repeated in the Laws (757c), where Plato explicitly defends the view that political justice is based on proportional equality.19 He explains that proportional equality involves granting �more to the greater per- son and less to the lesser person, adjusting what you give to take account of the nature of each�(tù men g¦r me�zoni ple�w, tù d/ �l£ttonismikrÒterÒtera n�mei m�tria didoàsa prÕj t¾n aÙtîn fÚsin �kat�rw) and that what �nature� is relevant depends on the kind of good being distributed.20 The idea of what one deserves or merits is very elastic, and one can adopt the idea of proportional equality while at the same time maintaining that all sorts of factors determine merit or worth in different cases. If prizes in a race are awarded, then merit is determined by swiftness.21 Or suppose people have associated in a business with different individuals contributing different amounts to the original investment.22 Other things being equal, profits are 17 πρÕj ti te�non(454b7); πρÕj aÙt¦ te�non t¦ �pithdeÚmata (454d1); πρÕj t�cnhtin¦ ½ ¥llo �pit»deuma (454d8; cf. 455a1). Cf. Aristotle�s reference to the �rgon in the pas- sage quoted above; and Plato�s reference to �rga which, he goes on to argue, the nature of a woman allows her to achieve in common with men (453a2). In so far as their natures are alike, it is fitting (pros»kei) to assign them the same task (�rgon) (453b10). � Note that, in these texts, ��rgon� refers to the task or job one is assigned, and this does not necessarily coincide with the end with regard to which it is decided what natures are appropriately assigned a specific job. But a distinction between work and its goal does not play any explicit role in Plato�s argument. 18 Cf. Laws 715b�c, and R. Maurer, Platons �Staat� und die Demokratie, pp. 75� 76. 19 Laws 756e�758a. 20 Laws 696a�b. 21 Pol. 1283a11�14. 22 EE 1242b11�15. Cf. Pol. 1280a25�31, Rep. 333a�b. SOCIAL JUSTICE IN PLATO�S REPUBLIC 29 distributed justly when they are distributed proportionately to the original sum invested, so that those who invested more get more in return, and those who invested less get less in return. Here again, the virtue or vice of the peo- ple involved is irrelevant to determining what counts as a just distribution of money. What determines one�s merit is the relative size of one�s original in- vestment. So it is easy to see how the idea of proportional equality can be made con- sistent with Plato�s decision about the distribution of the items Vlastos referred to in his argument. When the basic structure of the city is being de- cided, and the goods distributed to the members of the ideal polis are the rights to a normal sexual life and family life, and the right to own private property, then the goal with regard to which we decide what is just will be the overriding aim of the distribution of all goods in the city � the wellbeing of the city as a whole, which requires that the essential tasks in the city be per- formed as well as possible. With this goal in mind, one will merit what one needs to make one�s greatest contribution to the wellbeing of the city in the performance of one�s function, and one will not deserve any item which would threaten one�s ability to thus contribute to the wellbeing of the city. Since Plato believes that the items mentioned by Vlastos would harm the guardians� ability to rule, they are denied those goods � they do not merit them. In other words, the idea of proportional equality can absorb Vlastos� idea and say that, for the distribution of many goods, what one deserves at least partly depends on how the possession of that good affects one�s ability to do one�s job in contributing to the city�s wellbeing.23 (2) What I have just said also provides part of the answer to Vlastos� first objection to proportional equality in �Rights of Persons.�24 Consider, he says, a flutemaker in Plato�s ideal city with the skill to become much richer than other members of the producing class while working far less. FR explains why Plato would not allow the flutemaker to get away with this � having more money, property and leisure than others would not enable him to do his job any better, so he will not be allowed to have them. On the other hand, Vlastos claims, proportional equality will not explain Plato�s decision: �why shouldn�t the flutemaker claim that the merit of his superior talent is so much greater than [the talent] of mere shoemakers and the like that it entitles him to vastly greater social benefits?�25 So, according to Vlastos, FR explains why 23 Vlastos� second argument in �Rights of Persons� (pp. 117�18) is basically the same as the argument just considered, differing only in that the latter argument as- sumed that proportional equality positively demands that the guardians be given the goods which Plato denies them, while the argument in �Rights of Persons� merely claims that nothing in the idea of proportional equality can explain why Plato denies the guardians private property and a family. 24 �Rights of Persons�, p. 115. 25 Ibid. 30 R. HEINAMAN Plato rules out inequalities of a sort which proportional equality would toler- ate. The reply is that Plato can allow that in laying down a general policy for how much accumulation of wealth is to be permitted, and on how much ine- quality of wealth may exist, the effect of these factors on the ability of people to perform their work must be taken into account in deciding what people de- serve.26 Since, Plato believes, excessive wealth and leisure would render the flutemaker unfit to perform his function, he will not merit these goods and will not receive them. Thus in the Laws,27 we find that Plato appeals to pro- portional equality in ruling that neither poverty nor excessive wealth should be allowed in the city whose constitution is being devised. Later I will argue that Plato�s second argument for his account of social justice shows that FR is unable to handle the Republic�s position concerning private property. (3) In the guardian class, Plato thought that women should be treated in the same way as men. They would have the same rights to education, work, social intercourse, and the same sexual, legal and political rights as men. Ac- cording to Vlastos, Plato�s position is based on FR: �membership in the guardian class should be as open to women as to men . . . on the ground that biological femaleness is irrelevant for good performance in any recognized work role.�28 On the other hand, we can see, Vlastos says, that proportional equality will not yield these results by considering the Laws (756e�758a), where jus- tice is determined by proportional equality, and women no longer have the same legal, political or vocational rights which Plato granted them in the Re- public. How exactly Plato would have thought that the justice of these inequalities is validated by PE is unclear. What is clear is that this principle is so vague and loose that it can offer no resistance to them, while if FR were being applied it would have ruled them out as firmly here [in the Laws] as previ- ously in the R[epublic].29 There are four points to be made in response to this argument. First, I have already explained how the Republic�s defence of its treatment of women is very close in thought and language both to Aristotle�s account of justice in terms of proportional equality, and to the Laws� account of political justice in terms of proportional equality. Secondly, Vlastos� characterization of the position of women in the Laws is quite misleading. To support it, he refers to Glenn Morrow�s book, Plato�s Cretan City. But Morrow correctly points out that, in the Laws, �Women are 26 Rep. 421c�422a. 27 Laws 744a�745b. 28 �Rights of Persons�, p. 117. 29 Ibid. SOCIAL JUSTICE IN PLATO�S REPUBLIC 31 to share with men, to the greatest extent possible, in all the activities and du- ties of the state.�30 Thirdly, even setting aside these points, Vlastos would only have suc- ceeded in indicating that social justice is not exhausted by the idea of proportional equality. But that is clear in any case. As we have seen, the be- lief in proportional equality does not by itself determine what the goods are whose distribution is to be governed by proportional equality. Nor does it specify what factors are to be taken into consideration in determining the merit or worth of the people who are to receive the goods. Even if Vlastos� view of the position of women in the Laws were correct, Plato could have ac- cepted proportional equality in both the Republic and the Laws while changing his mind between the two dialogues on the question of what women merit � just as, between the two dialogues, he changed his mind on the ques- tion of what kind of political power philosophers merit.31 Finally, this objection can be thrown back at Vlastos, for FR fails to ex- plain why anyone, male or female, is given power in Plato�s ideal city. This will be explained in the second half of the paper. (See (7) in section II). (4) A final point which Vlastos makes is this: Nor is it clear how P[roportional] E[quality] could have sustained the sense of affectionate partnership between the powerful elite and the powerless mass which Plato is counting on to provide the morale of the just society . . . Fraternal solidarity is what he has in view, affection generated in a work- ing relationship where the sense of interdependence is heightened to the nth degree as each of the partners feels that his own work gets the benefit of the best that the others have it in them to give. It is the FR principle that provides the basis for the emotional unity of the class-stratified Platonic polis.32 This is a strange argument, for it seems clear that on this question FR ex- plains nothing and proportional equality is the relevant consideration. According to FR, �all members of the polis have equal right to those and only those benefits which are required for the optimal performance of their func- tion in the polis.�33 So if the Republic�s principle of distributive justice 30 G. Morrow, Plato�s Cretan City (Princeton, 1960), p. 331. See Laws 781b, 785b, 805a, c�d, 806c. This does not mean that the position of women is in all re- spects equivalent to that of men. See, for example, 937a. 31 See Laws 713c, 875a�d and 691c�d: If we disregard due proportion (tÕ m�trion) by giving anything what is too much for it, too much canvas to a boat, too much nutriment to a body, too much authority to a soul, the consequence is always shipwreck ... [I]ts issue is injustice ... No soul of man while young or accountable to no control, will ever be able to bear the burden of supreme power among men without tak- ing the taint of the worst spiritual disease, folly ... Hence it calls for a great legislator to forestall this danger by his insight into due proportion. 32 �Rights of Persons�, pp. 118�19. 33 �Rights of Persons�, p. 110. 32 R. HEINAMAN applies to the amount of love which citizens are entitled to, then FR yields the result that one is only entitled to that amount of affection from other members of the polis which is required to enable one to perform one�s job as well as possible. But it is extremely implausible to suggest that a shoemaker or a farmer, or a soldier or a guardian for that matter, could not perform his or her job as well as possible without a certain amount of affection. In reply it might be said that one will be able to perform one�s job better the greater one�s degree of psychological contentment, and, other things be- ing equal, the more love one is given the greater one�s contentment. Hence, the amount of love one receives will affect one�s ability to do one�s job. But there is no evidence that Plato sees the matter in these terms, and if he had, then he would also have had to admit that this provides no justification for a guardian receiving more love than a farmer. Both would benefit equally with regard to their ability to do their work from the affection they receive. Indeed, if �one�s work� is understood to include all of one�s social obliga- tions, then it is quite plausible to suggest that the farmer would benefit more than the guardian since the latter�s motivation to fulfil his obligations should be much less dependent on such external factors. So, on the basis of FR, there would be no reason to love the city�s guardians any more than the city�s low- liest farmers, even if the guardian is an exemplar of virtue and wisdom while the farmer is at the bottom of Plato�s scale of virtue. Such a position cannot be seriously attributed to Plato. Rather, the Sympo- sium shows that if distributive justice is meant to apply to the degree of love one accords different objects, it will be determined by the same principle which Vlastos concedes34 will govern the distribution of honour35 in Plato�s ideal city: proportional equality. The enlightened Platonic lover loves good things in proportion to the degree which they deserve or merit, namely in proportion to the degree of beauty and goodness which they exemplify (Sym- posium 210a�212a; cf. Republic 402d, Laws 757a5�b7). In Plato�s city, ties of affection are supposed to unite a citizen to people from different classes as well as to others from his or her own class. If we assume that the Sympo- sium�s account holds in the Republic, then we can say that one should love people in proportion to their merit. When A and B are equal in merit, A and B should love one another to the same degree. When A is B�s superior, then A deserves more love from B in proportion to the degree in which A is supe- rior to B. So if A is twice as valuable as B, then B should love A twice as much as A loves B.36 34 �Social Justice�, p. 88. 35 Cf. Aristotle, NE 1159a16�17: �Being loved appears to be close to being hon- oured.� 36 Cf. Aristotle�s account of love between unequals in terms of proportionality: EE VII.3; 1241b32�40, 1242b6�15; NE 1158b27�33, 1159a34�b2, 1161a20�22, 1162a15�16, b2�4, 1163a24�b18. SOCIAL JUSTICE IN PLATO�S REPUBLIC 33 I conclude that Vlastos� objections to the view that proportional equality governs political justice in the Republic are unsuccessful.37 The next section will point out some serious difficulties for FR. II Both before and after the Republic, in the Gorgias (508a)38 and in the Laws (756e�758a; cf. 744b�d), Plato refers to proportional equality in explaining justice. So if Vlastos were right, Plato would have twice shifted his position on the issue of social justice being considered here. While not impossible, it is more likely that Plato�s view remained consistent from the Gorgias to the Laws. More seriously, Vlastos must also claim that Plato�s position shifts within the Republic itself, since he concedes that proportional equality deter- mines the Republic�s account of political justice on two important points.39 (1) As Vlastos concedes,40 the distribution of honour in the city is not governed by FR but by proportional equality. Honour may not strike us as a particularly important good for just distribution, but in the Laws (744c) Plato mentions it as one of the goods whose distribution should be governed by 37 At one point (�Social Justice�, p. 88) Vlastos speaks as though he considers an- other weakness of the proportional equality interpretation to lie in the fact that it only applies to socially distributable compensations, and hence cannot govern the greatest good which the guardians enjoy, the contemplation of Forms. Whether or not there is some way in which this good could be thought to be controlled by social justice in so far as the leisure of the guardians is so controlled, I do not see how the fact that a cer- tain account of social justice only applies to socially distributable goods could be considered an objection against it. Furthermore, if, for the above reason, the distribu- tion of this good is thought to be determined by political justice, proportional equality can handle it for the same reason that FR can. Vlastos would presumably say that, ac- cording to FR, the guardians deserve this good because it enables them to perform their work properly. But proportional equality can say exactly the same thing. 38 Cf. Statesman 257a�b; Epistle 7, 326d. As Morrow says (Plato�s Cretan City, p. 524, n. 10), it is presumably proportional equality that is in question in Diogenes Laertius� report (III, 23) that Plato refused to construct a constitution for the Megala- politans because they were unwilling to accept equality. 39 It is also interesting to note that the author of the Magna Moralia (1194a6�25) affirms that proportional equality governs political justice in the Republic. Some further minor support for the proportional equality interpretation is that Si- monides� account of justice � expressed by Socrates at 332c as giving to each what is due (tÕ prosÁkon) � is never repudiated (cf., for example, Rep. 444b4; 474c1). Plato concludes (335e) that �if ... anyone tells us that it is just to give everyone his due, and he means by this that from the just man harm is due to his enemies and benefit due to his friends � the man which says this is not wise, for it is not true.� Plato �does not suggest that the rejection of Polemarchus� attempted interpretations of the Simonidean view requires rejection of the view itself.� (T. Irwin, Plato�s Ethics (Oxford, 1995), pp. 173). �tÕ prosÁkon� is the term Isocrates used in explaining proportional equality in Areop. 21�22: �that which gives to each man his due (tÕ prosÁkon).� 40 �Social Justice�, p. 88. See Rep. 414a, 415a. Cf. 425b. 34 R. HEINAMAN proportional equality. Likewise, Aristotle considers honour one of the goods of immediate concern for distributive justice.41 FR fails to explain the Republic�s distribution of this good. What does FR say? �All members of the polis have equal right to those and only those bene- fits which are required for the optimal performance of their function in the polis.� So, according to FR, the guardians should be honoured only to the ex- tent required to enable them to perform their job as well as possible. But that would mean that the guardians should not be honoured at all, since they should be able to perform their task of ruling independently of how much honour they receive. However, Plato thinks that they deserve and should re- ceive more honour than anyone else, and after their death they should be honoured as divinities or godlike men.42 Receiving honours after death obvi- ously does not contribute anything to anyone�s ability to perform a certain task, so it is clear that FR does not explain why Plato thinks this distribution of goods is just. On the other hand, proportional equality explains why the guardians should be honoured so much more than anyone else. One should receive the good of being honoured in proportion to one�s merit, and since the guardians deserve this honour so much more than others43 they will re- ceive a proportionately greater amount of it. It is equally obvious that proportional equality, not FR, is needed to ex- plain why neglect of the gods is regarded as unjust (443a): such behaviour fails to accord the gods their due; it does not deprive the gods of what they need to promote the city�s wellbeing. (2) Plato criticizes democracy on the basis of the assumption that propor- tional equality is the proper account of social justice. In the Laws, when defending proportional equality as the proper account of justice, he says that �equal treatment of the unequal ends in inequality when not qualified by due proportion.�44 At Republic 558c Plato objects that democracy distributes �a kind of equality to equals and unequals alike.�45 In ancient Greek democra- cies, political offices were distributed by lot to all the citizens in a city irrespective of their abilities. This is pointed out at Republic 557a where it is said that, in a democracy, the ruling offices are distributed on an equal basis, given, for the most part, by lot.46 So when Plato objects that democracy dis- 41 EN 11130b2, 31. 42 Rep. 465d�e, 503a, 540b�c. Cf. 468e�469b. �They will be billionaires of honour in the Platonic state.� Vlastos, �Social Justice�, p. 88. 43 Why they deserve this honour is not completely clear. Vlastos thinks it will be based on their contribution to the city�s wellbeing. 540b�c suggests that it may be based on their outstanding virtue and intelligence. 44 Laws 757a2�4. A.E. Taylor�s translation. Cf. 757d4�5. 45 Cf. Rep. 453e, 454b, 456b5�6; Gorgias 483c5�6; Aristotle, NE 1131a24. 46 Cf. 561a�c and the contrast drawn in the Laws (757b�e) between proportional equality and choosing by lot. SOCIAL JUSTICE IN PLATO�S REPUBLIC 35 tributes a kind of equality to equals and unequals alike, he is saying that equal power (cf. 557a4) in the city is distributed to unequals, i.e. the same power is given to two people despite the fact that the one person may deserve it less than the other in virtue of possessing less ability to rule. He is saying that it is wrong to distribute the same amount of power both to those who de- serve it, those who have the ability to rule, and to those who do not deserve it, those who lack any ability to rule.47 The implication is that Plato believes that political offices should be dis- tributed on the basis of proportional equality, i.e. the degree of political power one gets should be proportional to one�s ability to use it properly. This underlies the question he asks in justification of assigning political power to women as well as men: (456b5�6): �Must not the same occupations be given to the same natures?� Proportional equality provides the basis for the distribu- tion of political offices in Plato�s ideal state.48 (3) Plato�s second argument for his definition of social justice in Book IV, 433e�434a, shows that his conception of justice applies to the right to posses- sion of specific items of private property which one has acquired by legitimate means. Proportional equality explains this while in many cases FR does not. When the guardians act as judges in lawsuits, Plato says, they will aim at justice, and what they will aim for is �that no one have what belongs to oth- Rep. 557�58 shows that F. David Harvey is wrong when he says that Laws 756e� 758a is probably the earliest text to make a connection between arithmetical equality and the lot, in �Two Kinds of Equality�, Classica et Mediaevalia 26 (1965), p. 112. 47 The word Aristotle standardly uses to refer to the quality of a person which de- termines what good they deserve is �¢x�a�, �merit� or �worth� (see, e.g., NE V.3). In Rep. 434a�b, in his third argument for his definition of political justice, Plato explains that real harm � injustice � occurs to the city when someone with only the ability of a soldier tries to become a guardian, ¢n£xioj õn ν. Cf. Laws 744b6. 48 Cf. Derbalov, �Ursprungsmotive und Prinzipien der Platonischen Staatsden- kens�, p. 274, n. 54 and 276. Vlastos (�Social Justice�, p. 87) notes that Republic 558c is regularly referred to in support of the idea that proportional equality is upheld in the Republic, and he himself maintained this position in ΙΣΟΝΟΜΙΑ ΠΟΛΙΤΙΚΗ (in Pla- tonic Studies (Princeton, 1973), pp. 193�94). �Social Justice� still admits that 558c must be understood in terms of proportional equality, but Vlastos now claims (p. 87) that Plato�s appeal to the idea is only �momentary.� Given Vlastos� admission that the Republic also distributes honour according to proportional equality, he is in the posi- tion of maintaining that Plato is committed to proportional equality both before and after the Republic, but rejects it in the Republic even though the Republic occasionally appeals to it in deciding questions about justice. Republic 557�58 shows that Vlastos is wrong to suggest that Plato�s avoidance of the word �to �sÒthj � in Book IV of the Republic indicates Plato�s rejection of both the idea of proportional equality and the idea of arithmetical equality (�Rights of Persons�, p. 114). 557�58 uses the word while defending proportional equality. 36 R. HEINAMAN ers, nor be deprived of what belongs to him.�49 Suppose that A steals some- thing from B. How can we justify the assertion that it would be just for B to be in possession of this property? FR says B has a right �to those and only those benefits which are required for the optimal performance of [his] func- tion in the polis.� But it is not going to be true in every case that B will not be able to do his job as well if his property is not returned to him. So according to FR, when one can do one�s job as well without one�s stolen property being returned, it will not be just for one to possess that property again. But Plato, who characterizes a just situation as one where people both do and have their own, describes the situation where a person has been robbed (for example) as a case in which someone is deprived of �his own,� and someone else has what is not his own but what is another�s (�csi t¢llÒtria).50 That is, for Plato, such a situation is unjust. If justice is people having �their own,� where this is a matter of people having what they merit or deserve, then we can explain how the example fits Plato�s definition of justice. For one may deserve and have a right to property one has acquired in a legitimate manner.51 49 Note that �justice� here characterizes the situation which the judges aim at, not their own action, as in Vlastos� rewriting of the argument (�Social Justice�, pp. 75� 76). Plato argues that (i) the judges will aim at a situation where no one has what be- longs to another or is deprived of his own because (ii) such a situation is just. From (i) and (ii) he concludes that the having and doing of one�s own is justice. Vlastos claims (p. 76, n. 32) that in the argument as presented the conclusion is �a wild non sequitur�, apparently because he does not see how doing one�s own can get into the conclusion from (i) and (ii). The alleged difficulty is removed by noting that the situa- tion described in (i), where �no one has what belongs to another�, can exist only if everyone does his own, and hence is not �a busybody� (oÙ polupragmone�), i.e. does not take what belongs to another (as Vlastos himself appears to point out in �Justice and Happiness in the Republic�, Platonic Studies , pp. 121�22). Vlastos� revision of the argument turns the example into one where the justice at issue is a matter of what Aristotle called rectificatory justice, i.e. a feature of the judge�s action which rectifies the (distributively) unjust situation where the robber has what is not his own. But in Plato�s example �justice� rather characterizes the distribu- tively just situation which the judge hopes to bring about. 50433e7. At Rep. 344a�b, injustice exists when �temple robbers, kidnappers, housebreakers, defrauders, and thieves� take �what belongs to others (t−llÒtria).� At 360b�d, laying �hands on what belongs to others (tîn t−llotr�wn)� is the description of unjust behaviour. 51 A similar argument can be given for other examples of unjust behaviour men- tioned by Plato at 443a: betrayal, breaking of oaths, adultery, neglect of parents (cf. 463c�d), failure to care for the gods. Even when these actions do not damage the vic- tims� ability to do their work, the situation may be unjust because they have not been given their due. Likewise, Plato clearly does not think that bringing false charges is unjust (565e) solely because it hinders the ability of the accused to do their work; or that the sole reason why it is unjust for a younger man to strike an older man (465a�b) is that it would make it more difficult for the older man to carry out his work. SOCIAL JUSTICE IN PLATO�S REPUBLIC 37 The connection between the situation Plato envisages and the idea of pro- portional equality is clear from Aristotle�s discussion of distributive justice in Nicomachean Ethics V. The case Plato is talking about is one where, before the situation is rectified, someone has what is not his own and another person has been deprived of what is his own. The person who has grasped what is not his own is guilty of taking more than his due, of pleonex�a In Nico- machean Ethics V.1 and 2, it is the contrast with this notion of pleonex�a that Aristotle uses to explain the idea of particular justice, i.e. distributive justice, as opposed to generic justice. And he then goes on to explain distributive jus- tice in Nicomachean Ethics V.3 in terms of proportional equality.52 (4) In 520a�b, when the question is raised of whether it is just to require the philosophers to participate in the task of ruling the city, Socrates says the following: Consider that we won�t be doing injustice to the philosophers who come to be among us, but rather that we will say just things to them while compel- ling them besides to care for and guard the others. We�ll say that when such men come to be in other cities it is fitting for them not to participate in the labours of those cities. For they grow up spontaneously against the will of the regime in each; and a nature that grows by itself and doesn�t owe its rearing to anyone has justice on its side when it is not eager to pay In the case of justice, someone might reply by saying that if the city is indeed just, everyone will have only what they need to do their work well. So if they are robbed of anything, that will hinder them in performing their work. But while the Republic clearly has egalitarian leanings, there is no reason to believe that Plato thinks the just city can exist only if there is absolute equality of wealth between citizens who per- form the same work. The Laws too has egalitarian leanings, but it allows that members of the wealthiest class of citizens may have four times as much wealth as members of the poorest class. So in the just city either the robbed wealthier shoe- maker can still perform his work as well as before, or the poor shoemaker who is robbed did not possess everything he needed to do his job as well as possible. 52 In the Nicomachean Ethics (1132b11�18), Aristotle says: These names, both loss and gain, have come from voluntary exchange; for to have more than one�s own (tÕ men g¦r pl�on �cein ½ t¦ aØtoà) is called gaining, and to have less than one�s original share is called losing; e.g. in buying and selling and in all other matters in which the law has left people free to make their own terms; but when they get neither more nor less but just what belongs to themselves (aÙt¦ di' aÙtîn g�nhtai), they say that they have their own (t¦ aÙtîn fas�n �cein) and that they neither lose nor gain. So it is easy to see how the �having one�s own� formula can apply to the posses- sion of goods acquired in return for services rendered. Here Aristotle applies it to a case in which goods are exchanged, and one �has one�s own� if one receives goods equivalent in value to the goods surrendered to the other person. (Cf. also Laws 918a� b). Likewise, there is no problem in seeing how, in the case of involuntary exchange which occurs in the case of theft, the robber can be described as having what is an- other�s and the victim described as not having his own. 38 R. HEINAMAN off the price of rearing to anyone.53 But you we have begotten for your- selves and for the rest of the city like leaders and kings in hives; you have been better and more perfectly educated and are more able to participate in both lives. So you must go down, each in his turn . . . Note first that, in the just polis, the reason why it is just for the non- philosophers to receive the benefit of the philosophers� rule is not that they need it to do their jobs but the fact that the philosopher received a benefit from the non-philosophers in the past. This shows that the question of what one needs to perform one�s job is not the only consideration that must be taken into account in deciding what is just. (5) Vlastos can explain why the philosopher who grows up in a non-ideal city has no obligation to benefit others in the city by ruling them: not having �done their own� they have not fulfilled their obligations to him, and it is only if that condition is satisfied that they have the right to the good of being ruled by the philosopher. However, the fact that other citizens in the unjust polis have not done their own does not mean that they thereby forfeit all their rights.54 For example, Plato certainly does not think that philosophers living in non-ideal societies may justly murder or rob whoever fails to do their proper work. The problem for FR is that it cannot explain why. For the rights that it specifies are conditional on the persons in question performing �their work�. Recall that doing one�s own can refer not merely to the performance of one�s specific job but to the entire range of one�s public and private obliga- tions to other people. One might try to interpret Vlastos� position as being that one is entitled to certain rights to some degree corresponding to the de- gree to which one does one�s work in the broad sense, where this refers to the entire range of one�s obligations. But this is evidently not what Vlastos in- tended. For he believes that, in Plato�s view, the fact that one cannot carry out one�s assigned job by itself suffices for the loss of all of one�s rights. 53 At 496d Plato describes the philosopher who withdraws from the madness of public life in an unjust city as someone who �does his own.� So the definition of social justice does not have application solely in the ideal polis: there is a kind of behavior that is doing one�s own, is just, even in the non-ideal polis. 54 Perhaps Vlastos can be understood as arguing against this claim at the end of �Rights of Persons�, pp. 120�23, when he criticizes Plato on the grounds that FR fails to explain why all people �have equal right to share in those benefits which accrue to individuals from the general observance of moral rules� (p. 121). For example, it fails to explain why all have equal right to the benefits resulting from others� observing moral rules prohibiting murder and robbery. On FR, he says, your rights to such bene- fits depend on your performing your work role. In response, I am arguing that Vlastos� point rather brings out a problem with his own interpretation of Plato, viz. that Plato does not think all of your rights depend on your work, and this in two ways. (1) It is not the case that you are entitled only to whatever you need to perform a cer- tain job. (2) It is not the case that all or your rights depend on the performance of your job. SOCIAL JUSTICE IN PLATO�S REPUBLIC 39 Consider what would happen in this utopia if someone through no fault of his own were to cease being a public asset. One of the philosophers, let us say, becomes permanently disabled and can no longer do his job or any other work that would come anywhere near the expected level of produc- tive excellence . . . What may he then claim, now that he may no longer ground his claims on the needs of his job, but only on the value of his indi- vidual existence? As I read the Republic, the answer is: Nothing.55 Of course, the inability to do a specific job does not mean that one is no longer able to fulfil any of one�s moral obligations, and so the disabled phi- losopher could still continue to do some of the things that constitute �doing one�s own� in the extended sense. But as far as Vlastos is concerned, that would earn him no rights whatever. (6) Another problem for FR is that it is explicitly restricted to relations be- tween members of the polis, whereas Plato takes it for granted that the notion of justice that he is talking about applies to the relations between one city and another.56 Thus, he explains that it is not �just� for one Greek city to enslave another Greek city, or to allow any other city to do so (469b�c); nor is it just for one Greek city to ravage the countryside or to burn the houses belonging to other Greeks. On the other hand, Plato apparently thinks that there is no in- justice in a Greek city so treating a city that belongs to barbarians. Since FR does not apply to inter-city relations, it cannot explain Plato�s views about what is just and unjust in such cases. But Proportional Equality can: since Greeks are by nature friends, while Greeks and barbarians are natural ene- mies (470c�d), Greeks do not merit or deserve such treatment from other Greeks; but since Greeks and barbarians are alien in nature, barbarians do merit such treatment from Greeks. For the same reason, Proportional Equality explains why Plato believes it is unjust for a Greek soldier to enslave another Greek (469c). But it is hard to see how FR could always justify such a rule since a soldier would often be able to do his job better when assisted by a slave. (7) Vlastos says that the most important issue for the question of political justice is the distribution of political power: 55 �The Individual as Object of Love in Plato�, Platonic Studies, p. 15. Note that at 498b�c Plato envisages the guardians retiring from political duties and evidently sur- viving to study philosophy. And the kind of argument used in 520a�b suggests why Plato would consider it just to allow healthy individuals who are too old to work to continue to live from the goods provided by other citizens. In 520a�b Plato argues that it is just for the rest of the citizens to receive the good of the philosophers� rule in re- turn for the past benefits which the philosophers received from the citizens even though the future philosophers were at that time contributing little to the good of the city as a whole. Likewise, the past benefits which the elderly citizens conferred on the rest of the city can be the basis for the justice of others helping them now even though the elderly citizens are now contributing little to the overall good of the city. 56 Rep. 332e, 351b, 428d, 469b�471c. 40 R. HEINAMAN For Plato�s public the question concerning the rights of persons whose ur- gency remained paramount over that of all other public issues concerned the just allocation of political rights which, for the Greeks, meant the right to direct participation in functions of government and therewith a share in the control of the state.57 But a major defect with FR is that it gives us no answer to this question of how political offices should be distributed in the polis. Vlastos explains FR as follows: Plato�s unstated, but firmly followed, rule is that each has a right to those, and only those, socially distributable benefits which will maximize his contri- bution, regardless of the ratio which the value of services rendered bears to that of benefits received. . . . Given this model, and the collateral assumptions which Plato makes about what is best done by whom, the allocation of rights which produces the social structure of the rationally ordered polis of Plato�s vision be- comes completely lucid. 58 The italicized phrase refers to (i) assumptions about what functions are best done by whom, which are distinguished from (ii) the model of just distribution. This indicates Vlastos� tacit recognition of the fact that FR does not itself de- termine �what is best done by whom,� i.e. it does not determine what functions are assigned to which people in the city. Hence, it does not deter- mine who is assigned the job of ruling in the city. FR59 presupposes that 57 �Rights of Persons�, p. 113; cf. p. 114. 58 �Social Justice� p. 89. My italics. 59 Some other formulations: for people in the polis, �their function is sole title to the benefits distributed within the polis� (�Social Justice�, p. 90, n. 94). �All members of the polis have equal right to those and only those benefits which are required for the optimal performance of their function in the polis� (p. 110). �The only benefits one is now allowed of right from the cooperative interchange are those which are required for the optimal performance of one�s function� (�Social Justice�, p. 112). �[T]he mem- bers of the polis are to have only those rights which are required for the optimal performance of their respective function...� (�Social Justice�, p. 114). A person �can claim no benefit for himself except insofar as it would enable him to be a better pro- ducer� (�The Individual as an Object of Love in Plato�, Platonic Studies, p. 13). In his paper �Was Plato a Feminist?� (in Studies in Greek Philosophy, vol. II, p. 141), where his attention is on the justification for allowing women as guardians, Vlastos� formulation is significantly different: �the rights and duties justly allocated to citizens of the polis would be all and only those which would enable each of them to make the greatest personal contribution to the happiness and excellence of the whole polis� (my italics). If this is accepted, we need to know how we will distribute duties to the citizens in order to ensure that they do the work that makes the city as happy SOCIAL JUSTICE IN PLATO�S REPUBLIC 41 functions, including political offices, have already been distributed and so it cannot explain the pattern of distribution advocated by Plato. It says that what you deserve depends on what your function is � ruling, producing, etc. Hence, it answers the question of what goods should be distributed to a per- son on the basis of the assumption that that person has already been assigned a certain function. So Vlastos cannot explain why certain people should receive political power on the basis of FR. Before the assignment of a specific function they have no function the performance of which requires certain goods in order to be done as well as possible. We need an account of justice that is independent of FR to determine how political power is to be justly distributed. Vlastos does say something about the proper grounds for distributing po- litical offices. One qualifies for a certain role in the polis, he says, �by natural aptitude, by politically provided education, and by excellence of perform- ance.�60 �The right to participate in the functions of government . . ., like every social function, belongs by right to those who can do it best.�61 But then, of course, it is not one�s social function that grounds the assignment of social function. Rather, the assignment of a certain role in the city will be explained on the basis of proportional equality: one gets the job one merits or deserves � one gets the job one is best able to perform. Thus, Plato believes the guardians alone, because of their preeminent virtue and knowledge, possess the neces- sary ability to rule the city properly. Since everyone else merits or deserves no political power, everyone else gets no political power.62 The assignment of one�s job will be covered by the idea of distributive justice, but sometimes it appears that, for Plato, it is not a matter of distribut- ing goods, but rather a matter of distributing the burdens or �evils� which everyone must endure in a fair manner. This is certainly a matter for which the question of justice or injustice will arise,63 but FR only applies to the dis- tribution of benefits. Hence, it does not clearly apply to the distribution of political power, which, as Vlastos points out, the Republic regularly classifies as an example of a good which is intrinsically bad and possess merely in- strumental value.64 and excellent as possible. I am arguing that the distribution will be in accordance with proportional equality. 60 �Rights of Persons�, pp. 110�111. 61 �Social Justice�, p. 89. 62 Note, too, Plato's criticism of the basis of oligarchic rule at 551c: �would anyone appoint the pilots of a ship this way, by their wealth, and not entrust the ship to a poor man even if he was a better pilot?� 63 The Laws (744c) mentions �contributions� or taxes (e�sfora�) as one of the items whose distribution is governed by proportional equality. 64 Rep. 345d�347d, 517c�d, 519c�d, 520c�e, 521b, 540b. Vlastos says that the guardians �can be expected to make bigger sacrifices in personal happiness for the common good, the biggest of them being the very exercise of the right to govern, 42 R. HEINAMAN One final point. There will be no problem about the proportional equality interpretation accommodating Plato�s analogy between psychic justice and political justice. In the case of psychic justice, while Plato does speak in terms of distributing goods to parts of the soul by allowing them to experi- ence certain pleasures (586d-587a), the emphasis is on each part of the soul performing its proper task, on each part of the soul doing its own rather than having its own. Injustice exists in the soul when a lower part of the soul at- tempts to �rule in the soul although this is not proper (oÙ prosÁkon) since by nature it is fit (pr�pein) to be a slave.�65 The part of the soul which is properly assigned the task of ruling one�s life is reason. This deserves to rule (tÕ m�n which Plato thinks a painful bore� (�Social Justice�, p. 89.). It is hard, then, to see how Vlastos can also say that the performance of one�s work in the city �is for each of these people a privilege, an infinitely precious one, the basis of the worth and mean- ing of their life, so much so that if ... they were to become unfit to do their work, life would lose its value for them� (�Rights of Persons�, p. 112). Likewise, if ruling is a painful bore for the philosopher, how can it be that his vision of the Form of Justice �fills him with a passionate longing to make it the ordering principle of his own life and of the life of his polis� (�Social Justice�, p. 98; my italics)? When Vlastos speaks about justice in the city requiring a sharing of �burdens� as well as of benefits (�Social Justice�, p. 79), the heaviest burden would appear to be the performance of one�s job. If the guardians rightly consider ruling of no intrinsic value, it is even clearer that the work of the auxiliaries and producers would have no intrinsic value. How, then, can the performance of this work be �the basis of the worth and meaning of their life�? But the conflict in Vlastos� account of the value of one�s function does no more than mirror an unresolved conflict in Plato�s own position. The Republic is supposed to be demonstrating that doing what is just, including one�s work, is an intrinsic good (cf. 497a), and Plato does say that the performance of one�s job is necessary if one�s life is to be worth living (406d�407a). But Plato often regards the specific actions in which doing what is just is realized as intrinsic evils (as in the passages cited above), or at least as devoid of any intrinsic value (357c�d). Plato has no account of the rela- tion between doing what is just and, say, building a house, when one does what is just by building a house. Irwin tries to help Plato out by saying that all he needs to show is that the guardi- ans value ruling insofar as it is just action, not insofar as it is ruling (Plato�s Ethics, pp. 300�301). But this distinction is not found in Plato. And it is an evasion of the problem Plato ought to be facing. The view Plato aims to refute holds that doing injustice is good in itself while doing what is just is evil in itself. The adherents of this view do not think that an unjust action is good qua doing what is unjust and indiffer- ent or worse qua (e.g.) getting possession of gold. It is precisely because an unjust act is a matter of getting possession of another�s gold that it appears good. Likewise, do- ing what is just appears to be an evil because of the specific content of the action in which it is realized � insofar as it is handing over one�s money, for example � not insofar as it falls under the description �doing what is just.� On its own, the demonstration that handing over one�s money or ruling is worthwhile only qua doing what is just leaves the position of Plato's opponent untouched. It was not that aspect of the action which anyone found objectionable. 65 Rep. 444b4. Cf. 442b1�2. SOCIAL JUSTICE IN PLATO�S REPUBLIC 43 logistikù ¥rcein pros»kei)66 because it alone possesses wisdom and looks to the good of the whole soul (442c). On the other hand, the lowest part of the soul is entirely unfit to rule, and so it is assigned no role in ruling the life of the just person. In the just person, the task of ruling the soul is distributed ac- cording to proportional equality � according to merit. Since, with respect to ruling, reason has all the merit and appetite has none, appetite is the slave of reason in the just soul (444b4) as the producer is the slave of the guardian in the just state (590c�d; contrast 463b). Psychic justice exists when each part of the soul does its own, and each part of the soul does its own when it does that which is fitting for it to do (Ö pros»kei). Robert Heinaman UNIVERSITY COLLEGE LONDON 66 Rep. 441e4. Cf. 474b�c. work_dxgsto4fnnhm3mwfgir33gw6vm ---- BOOK REVIEW Comparative Criminal Justice (2nd edn.) Francis Pakes. Willan Publishing, Devon, UK, 2010: ISBN: 978-1-84392-769-3, v-ix + 212 pages, £20.99 (Paperback) Michael Adorjan Received: 16 August 2010 /Accepted: 18 August 2010 / Published online: 7 September 2010 # The Author(s) 2010. This article is published with open access at Springerlink.com Pakes’ book Comparative Criminal Justice is ambitious. The book provides a broad, topically geared and internationally comparative introduction to criminal justice. It follows a tried-and-true yet practical progression from policing, pre-trial and trial systems, punishment, and finishing with chapters on international policing and the development of universal human rights and international courts of justice. Each chapter offers a general introduction to areas that are then elaborated with reference to differing cultural contexts. Case studies are frequently presented in boxes that help flesh out the main arteries of thought, and often help introduce further comparisons and contrasts. The book is most suitable for undergraduate students, though its insights may appeal to a broad readership, including criminal justice practitioners and those involved in policy. The strongest feature of Comparative Criminal Justice is its inclusiveness. Pakes underscores at several points his argument that a comprehensive comparative lens must take into account both quantitative and qualitative approaches (p. 9); that “the question of meaning remains highly pertinent” (p. 30); and that no matter how global our perspective, we should be carefully attuned to the local exigencies of culture under which globalization trends in criminal justice are appropriated and attuned. This is the second edition of the book, featuring reference to current events [e.g., discussion of Obama’s potential recognition of the International Criminal Court (p. 179)]. Pakes aims to go “beyond police, courts and prisons” (p. 1) by including discussion on, for example, privatized policing and security, criminal justice in the Middle East (including Sharia law), and cybercrime, including reference to the ‘great firewall of China’. The best chapter opening is for the chapter on systems of trial (p. 86). Pakes begins with an elaborated discussion on the ergonomic features and layout of courtrooms, suggesting that the spatial relationships of courtrooms, for instance the placement of defendant in relation to the judge, illustrates much about the style and operation of the court system— especially when comparing adversarial and inquisitorial systems. Pakes sustains his references to ergonomics throughout the chapter, which serves to underscore theoretical and conceptual points. This proves to be a pedagogically effective approach. Asian Criminology (2012) 7:193–195 DOI 10.1007/s11417-010-9094-3 M. Adorjan (*) Department of Sociology, The University of Hong Kong, Pokfulam Road, Pokfulam, Hong Kong e-mail: madorjan@hku.hk A consistent theoretical thread is upheld throughout the book regarding the differences, advantages and disadvantages of adversarial and inquisitorial judicial systems. During discussions about which nations gravitate towards which system, Pakes successfully underscores why certain international criminal justice initiatives (such as international tribunals) encounter problems: they pool actors from different cultural contexts who hold differing approaches. Part of the way forward, Pakes implies, involves understanding the geo-historical roots that have shaped variegated systems worldwide, and arriving at compromises that work. Another theoretical point with resonance is his frequent referrals to levels of trust or distrust in governments and crime control authorities. Pakes argues that “the type of person society decides to put its faith in with regard to dealing with alleged wrongdoers hinges on the answer to the question of whom to trust” (p. 120). Perhaps the work of David Nelken should be more prominent here, given Nelken’s advocacy of research on trust to further comparative criminology. Nevertheless, while never a central point, it becomes obvious that nations with neoliberal systems often hold higher levels of distrust, leading to particular crime control responses (penal populism is discussed in the chapter on punishment). It is equally obvious that nations with higher levels of trust in the state and crime control respond quite differently to crime. Pakes is quick, however, to offer up-to-date evidence that, for instance, the ‘rosy’ image of crime control in the Netherlands needs tempering in light of recent evidence challenging the region’s classic reluctance to rely on imprisonment (p. 130). Pakes is critical towards theories of globalization, arguing that there still exists an enormous gap between those with access to information technologies and the advantages of ‘space-time compression’ (p. 151) and those left out (and left ‘local’). He notes, “against global winners we must set large groups of clearly identifiable global ‘have nots’” (p. 153). For all the discussion on globalization, however, I found it surprising that no reference is made to Bauman’s writings, especially on ‘glocalization’. It would be worthwhile to make this connection considering Pakes’ already developed analyses on local–global intercon- nections and limitations. As Pakes says, “we can continue to look at national or local arrangements but we must be aware of the fact that globalisation also impacts on [them]” (p. 21), adding “the differential impact of globalisation on local communities is a key area of comparative research” (p. 22). Pakes is likely well aware of areas where more theoretical muscle could be added, but chooses to refrain to make the text accessible to an undergraduate student audience. Nevertheless, student receptivity to theoretical criminology should not be underestimated. It is interesting to consider whether an effective comparative analysis is enabled by a value neutral or critical orientation. Pakes is certainly value neutral (for the most part), especially when carefully discussing the details of Sharia law and Islamic systems of crime control (pp. 96–99). He states facts associated with gender disparities here without making further critical remarks: “In most Islamic courts evidence from a male witness counts heavier than that from a female witness and in some jurisdictions women hardly appear at all as witnesses” (p. 98). His non-judgmental analysis allows readers to consider complexities and ambiguities and ultimately make up their own minds. As he notes, such an analysis may help prevent ethnocentrism (p. 3). In some locations, however, Pakes’ political and critical leanings are more evident: e.g., in his reference to Kenya as a nation that “ridicules the notion of ‘free’ state police” (p. 57); or in his reference to the “pervers [ity]” that in the Netherlands suspects’ rights are “severely limited” due to the feeling that “the presence of a defense lawyer would hinder the development of rapport between interviewer and suspect” (p. 75). It may be, indeed, safer to critique Western criminal justice systems than Islamic systems animated more by religion than legal protocol. Pakes 194 Asian Criminology (2012) 7:193–195 seems to be deliberately holding back his criticisms of Islamic systems, but does so likely to promote empathy and understanding. As Pakes notes at the end of this chapter, “there is no easy way of judging which [system] is better or worse. That would probably be a meaningless exercise” (p. 103). The reader will be left to decide if Pakes could (and should) be more critical here in the same manner as he is—with much greater ease—with respect to occidental regions. Pakes asserts that despite pressure on scholars of comparative criminal justice to be experts on everything, this is impossible (p. 11); indeed a book on comparative criminal justice should not try to be everything to everyone, for too much would be lost. Nevertheless, there are areas where minor mistakes are made that may be more noticeable to readers in Southeast Asia. For instance Pakes incorrectly asserts that Hong Kong’s Independent Commission Against Corruption was founded in 1994 (p. 56), when in fact (referring to the same ICAC source Pakes himself cites) it was founded in 1974. This has implications for the discussion, as Pakes refers in this section to the 1990s, not the 1970s, as a period during which Hong Kong was embroiled in “the fight against corruption,” which took “centre stage” (p. 56), and discusses ICAC statistics as recent as 2009. I also feel that Pakes presents too uncritically the ‘zero tolerance’ success of New York City during the 1990s under mayor Giuliani (pp. 51–52). He may have at least referred to skeptics who have pointed to trends indicating declining crime rates before Giuliani took office. Overall, however, these points are minor quibbles and in no manner detract from the validity and rigorous scholarship that runs consistently throughout the text. Readers interested in Hong Kong and China may note Pakes’ attention to these areas. Hong Kong’s recent inclusion in the United National International Crime Victims Survey facilitates this. Pakes’ discussion of Internet censorship in China via its ‘great firewall’ is given balanced treatment. He refers to the initiative’s real name, the Golden Shield Project, and presents a series of facts about it while reserving judgement (p. 160). While readers invested in researching these areas will not be satisfied about the attention they receive (short paragraphs embedded in larger comparative discussions), this is to be expected in a book that is careful not to place too much emphasis on any particular area. While Asian and Middle Eastern regions receive attention, the book is often more robust in its intra-regional comparisons within Europe, with frequent references to the US as well. This is obviously due to Pakes’ experience researching these areas, though more sustained attention to areas outside of Western domains would help underscore insights Pakes makes in reference to neoliberalism (p. 151) and nations that do not seem to follow the same neoliberal patterns of certain Western regions. Comparative Criminal Justice may serve its purposes best as a springboard to both classroom discussion and further research. It is evident that comparative criminology is still an emerging area, with questions and criticisms regarding methods, theories, and whether or not a more critically oriented engagement is appropriate. Pakes guards against critical approaches, perhaps due to reservations that a descent into pejorative assessments would stymie the ability to explore culturally specific meanings. The book is a success, in any event, which helps to break readers out of ostensibly myopic criminological research. Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution Noncommercial License which permits any noncommercial use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author(s) and source are credited. Asian Criminology (2012) 7:193–195 195 Comparative Criminal Justice (2nd edn.) work_dznjlx7anjh4pmg6eziere6ori ---- PowerPoint-Präsentation Using Factorial Surveys to Study Justice Perceptions: Five Methodological Problems of Attitudinal Justice Research SFB 882 Working Paper Series ○ No. 47 ○ January 2015 DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities http://www.sfb882.uni-bielefeld.de/ Stefan Liebig Carsten Sauer Stefan Friedhoff Stefan Liebig, Carsten Sauer and Stefan Friedhoff Using Factorial Surveys to Study Justice Perceptions: Five Methodological Problems of Attitudinal Justice Research SFB 882 Working Paper Series, No. 47 DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities Research Project A6 Bielefeld, January 2015 SFB 882 Working Paper Series General Editors: Martin Diewald, Thomas Faist and Stefan Liebig ISSN 2193-9624 This publication has been funded by the German Research Foundation (DFG). SFB 882 Working Papers are refereed scholarly papers. Submissions are reviewed by peers in a two-stage SFB 882 internal and external refereeing process before a final decision on publication is made. The Working Paper Series is a forum for presenting works in progress. Readers should communicate comments on the manuscript directly to the author(s). The papers can be downloaded from the SFB 882 website http://www.sfb882.uni-bielefeld.de/ SFB 882 “From Heterogeneities to Inequalities” University of Bielefeld Faculty of Sociology PO Box 100131 D-33501 Bielefeld Germany Phone: +49-(0)521-106-4942 or +49-(0)521-106-4613 Email: office.sfb882@uni-bielefeld.de Web: http://www.sfb882.uni-bielefeld.de/ DFG Research Center (SFB) “From Heterogeneities to Inequalities” Whether fat or thin, male or female, young or old – people are different. Alongside their physi- cal features, they also differ in terms of nationality and ethnicity; in their cultural preferences, lifestyles, attitudes, orientations, and philosophies; in their competencies, qualifications, and traits; and in their professions. But how do such heterogeneities lead to social inequalities? What are the social mechanisms that underlie this process? These are the questions pursued by the DFG Research Center (Sonderforschungsbereich (SFB)) “From Heterogeneities to Inequalities” at Bielefeld University, which was approved by the German Research Foundation (DFG) as “SFB 882” on May 25, 2011. In the social sciences, research on inequality is dispersed across different research fields such as education, the labor market, equality, migration, health, or gender. One goal of the SFB is to integrate these fields, searching for common mechanisms in the emergence of inequality that can be compiled into a typology. More than fifty senior and junior researchers and the Bielefeld University Library are involved in the SFB. Along with sociologists, it brings together scholars from the Bielefeld University faculties of Business Administration and Economics, Educational Science, Health Science, and Law, as well as from the German Institute for Economic Research (DIW) in Berlin and the University of Erlangen-Nuremberg. In addition to carrying out research, the SFB is concerned to nurture new academic talent, and therefore provides doctoral training in its own integrated Research Training Group. A data infrastructure project has also been launched to archive, prepare, and disseminate the data gathered. Research Project A6 “The Legitimation of Inequalities – Structural Conditions of Justice Attitudes over the Life-span” This project investigates (a) the conditions under which inequalities are perceived as problems of justice and (b) how embedment in different social contexts influences the formation of attitudes to justice across the life course. We assume that individuals evaluate inequalities in terms of whether they consider them just, and that they hold particular attitudes toward justice because, and as long as, these help them to attain their fundamental goals and to solve, especially, the problems that arise through cooperation with other people (cooperative relations). As a result, attitudes on justice are not viewed either as rigidly stable orientations across the life span or as “Sunday best beliefs” i.e. short-lived opinions that are adjusted continuously to fit situational interests. Instead, they are regarded as being shaped by the opportunities for learning and making comparisons in different phases of the life course and different social contexts. The goal of the project is to use longitudinal survey data to explain why individuals have particular notions of justice. The key aspect is taken to be changes in the social context – particularly households, social networks, or workplaces – in which individuals are embedded across their life course. This is because social contexts offer opportunities to make social comparisons and engage in social learning, processes that are decisive in the formation of particular attitudes to justice. The project will test this empirically by setting up a special longitudinal panel in which the same individuals will be interviewed three times over an 11- year period. The results of the project will permit conclusions to be drawn on the consequences of changes in a society's social and economic structure for its members' ideas about justice. The project therefore supplements the analysis of the mechanisms that produce inequality, which is the focus of SFB 882 as a whole, by looking at subjective evaluations, and it complements that focus by addressing the mechanisms of attitude formation. Research goals (1) Analysis of the conditions in which justice is used as a criterion for evaluating inequalities. (2) Explanation of attitudes toward justice as the outcome of comparison and learning processes mediated by the social context. (3) Longitudinal observation of the individual development of attitudes to justice over the life course. Research design (1) Continuation and expansion of the longitudinal survey of evaluations of justice conducted by the German Socio-Economic Panel Study (SOEP). (2) Commencement of an independent longitudinal panel with ties to the process-generated individual data of the German Institute for Employment Research (IAB) and information on companies and households (the plan is to carry out three survey waves over an 11-year period). The Authors Stefan Liebig is Professor of Sociology with a special focus on Social Inequality and Social Stratification at the Faculty of Sociology, Bielefeld University, and Principal Investigator of the Collaborative Research Centre (SFB) 882 research project A6, “The Legitimation of Inequalities – Structural Conditions of Justice Attitudes over the Life-span”. His research interests are empirical justice research, organizations and social inequality, and methods of empirical research. Recent publications are “The justice of earnings in dual-earner households”, in: Research in Social Stratification and Mobility 30 (2012): 219-232 (with C. Sauer and J. Schupp); “Gerechtigkeit”, in: S. Mau & N. M. Schöneck (Eds.), Handwörterbuch zur Gesellschaft Deutschlands (2013), Springer VS: 286-299 (with C. Sauer and P. Valet); “The Application of Factorial Surveys in General Population Samples: The Effects of Respondent Age and Education on Response Times and Response Consistency”, in: Survey Research Methods 5 (2011): 89-102 (with C. Sauer, K. Auspurg and T. Hinz). Contact: stefan.liebig@uni-bielefeld.de Carsten Sauer is a postdoctoral research fellow in the SFB 882, project A6 at Bielefeld University. His research interests include the explanation of behavior, social inequality and justice and quantitative research methods (especially factorial surveys). Among his recent publications are: “The Factorial Survey as a Method for Measuring Sensitive Issues”, in: U. Engel, B. Jann, P. Lynn, A. Scherpenzeel, P. Sturgis, (Eds.), Improving Survey Methods. Lessons from recent Research (2014), Routledge: 137-149 (with K. Auspurg, T. Hinz, S. Liebig); “Incentives and Inhibitors of Abusing Academic Positions: Analysing University Students' Decisions about Bribing Academic Staff”, in: European Sociological Review 30 (2014): 230-241 (with P. Graeff, S. Satter, G. Mehlkop); “Less is Sometimes More: Consequences of Overpayment on Job Satisfaction and Absenteeism”, in: Social Justice Research 26 (2013): 132-150 (with P. Valet); “When Decisions Should Be Shared: A Study of Social Norms in Medical Decision Making Using a Factorial Survey Approach”, in: Medical Decision Making 33 (2013): 37-47 (with M. Müller-Engelmann et al.). Contact: carsten.sauer@uni-bielefeld.de Stefan Friedhoff is a member of the SFB 882 project “Information and Data Infrastructure” (INF) and PhD candidate at the Bielefeld Graduate School in History and Sociology (BGHS). In the INF project he assists researchers with problems of everyday documentation and improves documentation practices. His research interests focus on data management, survey methodology, social inequalities and factorial survey research. Contact: stefan.friedhoff@uni-bielefeld.de Using Factorial Surveys to Study Justice Perceptions: Five Methodological Problems of Attitudinal Justice Research Stefan Liebig, Carsten Sauer, and Stefan Friedhoff1 Summary: This article provides an overview of how factorial surveys have been used in justice research in the past. It addresses the question of why this method is particularly useful to survey attitudes toward justice. This question is discussed with reference to five problems of empirical justice research. For each of these problems, findings are presented from recent justice research that has used the factorial survey method, with a focus on assessing the allocation and distribution of goods (earnings/income, transfer payments, pensions) and burdens (taxes). The paper concludes with a discussion of future developments and possible applications in this research field. Introduction For a long time, the question of what is just and what is not was regarded as a purely normative problem and, thus, as a subject of philosophy, legal theory, or theology. The aim of this normative justice research is to provide answers to Kant’s question “What ought I to do?”, and to do so has to identify principles or rules of justice that ensure that, from a moral point of view, the allocation and distribution of goods and burdens can be regarded as just (e.g., Rawls, 1975). Starting around the middle of the last century, a descriptive, or empirical, line of research on justice began to establish itself, first in psychology, and later in the social sciences and in economics (Adams, 1965; Deutsch, 1985; Jasso, 1978; Runciman, 1966; Törnblom, 1992). This steadily growing line of research examines what individuals and societies consider to be a just distribution of goods and burdens; why a state of justice is regarded as something worth achieving; and what consequences can be observed in a society when something is perceived as just or injust. Most of this empirical research has focused on the study of attitudes toward procedural and distributive justice (cf. Liebig & Sauer, 2013, 2015). While questions of procedural justice involve an evaluation of decision-making processes regarding the allocation and distribution of goods or burdens (Deutsch, 1985; Jasso, 1980; Törnblom, 1992; Wegener, 1987), questions of distributive justice involve an evaluation of the outcomes of such processes. The main finding of this research is that attitudes toward or beliefs about justice, as well as evaluations of concrete outcomes, not only depend on individual characteristics—and thus do not have the status of personal traits—but are affected by the social situation in which an individual is embedded and the type of resource that is allocated. A specific allocation amount can therefore only be assessed on the basis of contextual information (Hegtvedt, 2006). This is why judgments concerning distributive justice are always complex, context- dependent, and context-related attitudes. At least five methodological problems result from this complexity which are partially known from other areas of attitude research but are particularly important in justice research. First, the high degree of context dependency of judgments implies that a lack of contextualization can lead to systematically biased measurements of attitudes toward justice, particularly in survey-based justice research, but also in experimental behavioral economics, where researchers deduce individual attitudes toward justice from behavior in very abstract and artificial distribution situations. Second, since attitudes toward justice appear to be determined by a variety of very different factors, the actual importance and, especially, the relative importance of these factors must be determined (for example, to draw conclusions about their role in the generation of distributive injustices). This leads 1 This paper is an outcome of the research project “The Legitimation of Inequalities – Structural Conditions of Justice Attitudes over the Lifespan,” which is funded by the German Research Foundation (DFG) within the Collaborative Research Center 882 “From Heterogeneities to Inequalities” at Bielefeld University, Germany. 1 us to a third problem: in order to investigate the causes and influencing factors of individual perceptions of justice, in some fields of justice research, experimental studies are conducted in the laboratory, with only a certain group of individuals—usually students—participating (Henrich et al., 2010). As a result, the findings are often based on the study of convenience samples which include students and in which the external validity is usually not sufficiently clarified. This is particularly problematic in justice research because there is evidence that individual attitudes toward justice are influenced by sociostructural position and previous individual experiences, among other things. The fourth problem, the problem of social-desirability bias in response behavior (Paulhus, 1984), is particularly important when measuring attitudes toward justice because attitudes are sometimes not measured appropriately, so that the findings obtained lead to erroneous conclusions. The fifth problem is the problem of measuring and identifying causal relationships; this problem is particularly relevant when conducting research on the causes of certain attitudes, whether toward justice or other factors. In this article, we will show how factorial surveys can be used, if not to overcome, then at least to reduce, the risk and impact of these five problems in empirical research on justice. We will review studies that analyze attitudes toward distributive justice and report problems in relation to the illustrated key results.2 The article concludes with a discussion of future developments and possible applications. Factorial Surveys in Empirical Justice Research Factorial surveys have been used in empirical justice research for over 30 years to determine what ideas exist about the fair allocation of goods or burdens (e.g., Beck & Opp, 2001; Jasso, 2006; Rossi & Anderson, 1982; Wallander, 2009). Generally speaking, respondents in these studies are asked to evaluate short descriptions (“vignettes”) of recipients (e.g., employees, households), in which the individual or situational characteristics (“dimensions”) used to describe the case are varied systematically in their levels. Since these levels are simultaneously changed among vignettes, the procedure is also referred to as “multifactorial.” Figure 1 shows a vignette that is used to measure attitudes toward the distributive justice of income. The description consists of five dimensions, four of which are characteristics describing the individual (age, gender, vocational training, occupation), with the fifth dimension indicating the individual’s gross earnings. The specific values of these characteristics are varied from vignette to vignette. Respondents are then asked to rate the justice of the gross earnings presented on an 11-point scale. In the analysis, these ratings are treated as dependent variables, and the five dimensions are treated as independent variables. By systematically varying these dimensions, their importance for justice evaluations can be estimated through statistical analysis and conclusions about justice can be drawn, with questions that can be addressed in this way including: Should earnings increase with age? Should women receive the same income as men? Should individuals with vocational training earn more than individuals without training? 2 The following illustration is based on a literature review that involved two steps. The first step was to search for articles in Google Scholar and the Social Science Citation Index which use any combination of the German and English keywords “justice” or “fairness” [“Gerechtigkeit”] and “factorial survey” [“faktorieller Survey”] or “vignette(s)” [“Vignette(n)”]. Following the procedure described by Wallander (2009), the results were then complemented by publications citing the article “Who Should Get What? Fairness Judgments of the Distribution of Earnings” by Alves and Rossi (1978), because it is one of the first and most frequently cited articles in justice research that use factorial surveys. 19 articles in German and English were identified in this way. An overview of the studies used here can be found in the Appendix. 2 Figure 1. Example vignette with five dimensions A 60-year-old woman with occupational training works as a social-worker. Her gross monthly earnings are €2,500 (before taxes and transfers). In your opinion, are her monthly gross earnings just, unjustly high, or unjustly low? Unjustly low Just Unjustly high -5 -4 -3 -2 -1 0 +1 +2 +3 +4 +5            Source: Sauer et al. (2011) In the past, factorial surveys have been used in justice research primarily to examine attitudes toward the allocation of monetary rewards (individual earnings, household income, welfare-state transfer payments) or burdens (taxes). Compared with the use of vignettes in other fields of research (e.g., Wallander, 2009), the proportion of factorial surveys used in population surveys is larger in justice research, and there are also more international comparative studies (Auspurg et al., 2013; Hysom & Fişek, 2011; Jasso & Meyersson Milgrom, 2008; Schrenker, 2009). Recent applications of factorial surveys in justice research show two methodological peculiarities. (1) As regards the decisive advantage of factorial surveys, which is to provide the respondents with contextualizing information, studies differ in the number of dimensions (information content) and vignettes per respondent. The numbers of dimensions used per vignette range from three (Jann, 2008) to ten (Auspurg et al., 2013; Gatskova, 2013; Sauer et al., 2009). The number of vignettes to be evaluated varies much more. This is due to a methodological peculiarity. Especially in the early days of using factorial surveys, a very large number of vignettes were presented; the studies of Jasso, Rossi, and their colleagues used between 40 and 60 vignettes per respondent (Alves & Rossi, 1978; Jasso, 1994; Jasso & Meyersson Milgrom, 2008; Jasso & Rossi, 1977; Jasso & Webster, 1997). They did so because they wanted to obtain as many data points as possible for each subject to improve the estimation of individual judgment behavior (within-analysis) and to make comparisons among respondents based on their judgments (between-analysis). This procedure involves a two-step process. In the first step, individual regressions are estimated to measure the influence of the dimensions on the justice judgments of a single respondent (within-estimation). In the second step, these coefficients are used as individual traits to analyze correlations or differences among groups of respondents or other attitude measurements (between-estimation). (2) The second methodological peculiarity has to do with the use of open and magnitude response scales, which are used to avoid direct measurement. When asked the direct question, respondents state what they think would be a just reward the individual described in the vignette should receive (Hysom & Fişek, 2011; Shepelak & Alwin, 1986). When the respondents are asked the indirect question, the justice evaluation (amount of injustice) is measured, but the respondents are not asked to specify the reward (e.g., earnings). The actual amount is determined ex-post using a two-step estimation procedure. A classic application is the determination of the just amount of earnings (for details, see Jasso, 2006; Jasso & Meyersson Milgrom, 2008; Jasso & Wegener, 1997). This procedure is based on the theory of Jasso (1978, 2006), according to which the justice evaluation J is the product of the logarithmic ratio of the actual earnings (A) and the just earnings (C), as well as an individual constant (θ) (Jiv = θi × ln (Av / Civ), with i = judging individual and v = vignette). Both 3 C and θ are unknown and must be estimated. To calculate the just reward C, it is necessary to transform Jasso’s equation (Civ = Av × exp (–Jiv / θi)) and estimate θ as the slope coefficient of individual regression equations.3 The estimation is done by regressing individual-specific bivariate regressions of all judgments of an individual (J) on the actual earnings given in the vignettes. The estimated slope coefficient then provides the individual constant θ, which is used to calculate the just earnings for each vignette. This procedure makes it possible to express the attitudes toward justice in the reward units (see Figure 2). It is obvious that in this procedure at least an interval scale level of the justice judgment J is needed. For this reason in particular, open scales or magnitude scales are used (Jasso & Meyersson Milgrom, 2008; Jasso & Webster, 1999; Liebig & Mau, 2002, 2005) in addition to conventional 9- or 11-point rating scales (Alves & Rossi, 1978; Jasso, 1994; Jasso & Rossi, 1977; Jasso & Webster, 1997; Schrenker, 2009).4 The rationale for using these indirect measures of attitudes toward justice is that certain groups of respondents might find it too difficult to state specific rewards or burdens. More important, respondents do not express their own perceptions when asked about just rewards, because they are too heavily influenced by the given rewards (Jasso, 2006; for arguments to the contrary, see Markovsky & Eriksson, 2012). However, this method has been critically discussed (Auspurg & Hinz 2015), and the use of open or magnitude scales has been considered to be particularly problematic (Sauer et al., 2009, 2014). But how might factorial surveys be used to reduce the methodological problems of empirical research on justice? In the following, we will provide a detailed description of the five problems mentioned and explain how factorial surveys might be used to reduce these problems in justice research. Issues of Empirical Justice Research and Findings from Studies Involving Factorial Surveys Contextual Information: Complexity of Distribution Processes The first problem of analytical justice attitude research is rooted in the very subject itself. In most cases, the question of whether or not the allocation of certain rewards or burdens is just can be answered only on the basis of contextual information (Hegtvedt, 2006). This is because the actual allocation of rewards and burdens itself depends on a combination of individual and structural characteristics. The amount of actual earnings is determined by various factors, including individual performance, human capital, age, gender, occupation, industrial sector, and company size. The questions that arise when the justice of earnings is assessed are which of these factors the respondents think determine the amount of fair earnings and what relative importance each dimension has. Previous research shows that individuals judge allocation and distribution results on the basis of very general rules or principles of distribution, which also specify which dimensions the respondents will consider to what extent. The most important principles besides the principle of equality are the proportionality or equity principle (rewards should be proportional to an individual’s current expenses and efforts), the principle of need (individual requirements in terms of minimum social standards and non-self-inflicted disadvantages should be considered in the allocation), and the principle of entitlement (an individual’s position and status in the hierarchical structure of a society or a group should be taken into consideration) (Liebig & Sauer, 2013, 2015). The respondents’ decision as to which of these principles should guide the allocation or distribution process depends on the situation and on the type of goods or burdens to be distributed (e.g., income, 3 The equation is solved using the following conversion and Slutsky’s theorem: J = θ × ln A – θ × ln C = a + θ × ln A (cf. Jasso, 2007; Jasso & Wegener, 1997). 4 When the magnitude scale is used, respondents are asked to express the degree of their feeling of injustice by giving a random number or by drawing a line. To ensure the comparability of judgments, the respondents are first presented with a vignette (anchor vignette), which is similar for all respondents. 4 medical assistance). In making such decisions, respondents might also use a combination of any of these principles. It is important to note that there is no way any of these principles could be “simply” applied, because it is impossible to make generalized statements about what “individual performance” actually is, which of the criteria required are legitimate, or which status characteristics of an individual should be rewarded and with what amounts. This more precise determination of the conditions and their links to specific reward amounts in turn depends on the context, and is the result, of social-comparison processes. Only by comparing themselves with other individuals or groups (individual reference individuals or “generalized others”) can respondents develop concrete ideas about what might constitute a just reward or burden. Thus, information on the recipients and the situational conditions is needed to decide which principles of justice should apply in a given case and what reward or burden is just or unjust. Survey-based justice research in particular relies primarily on item-based measurement instruments, which provide respondents with little contextual information and measure attitudes toward justice on a very general and abstract level.5 The aim of these measurements is to identify cross-context preferences or general normative orientations.6 Item-based measurements are useful, generally speaking, but can also lead to a systematic distortion of response behavior. Since item-based instruments are designed to evoke a response behavior that favors equal distributions of goods and burdens, their exclusive use could lead to an overestimation of equality preferences. Studies on empirical justice research show that respondents always rely on “equality heuristics” if there is too little information about distributive decisions. A similar behavior is observed when the respondents want to or can invest only little cognitive capacity in processing the instruments used because the instruments are too abstract, too difficult to comprehend, or not concise enough (Keller et al., 2013; Messick, 1993; Roch et al., 2000). The use of the equality principle can be understood as a “rule of thumb or an intuitive rule of sharing” (Keller et al., 2013, p. 172) and as what might be called the “default” attitude in resolving allocation and distribution conflicts in “ambiguous, novel, or complex social situations” (Messick, 1993, p. 28). The advantage is that when using the equality principle, no information is needed about the recipients of the allocation or distribution or about any other situational parameters. Nor are there any complex cognitive processes required of the respondents to be able to make a more differentiated allocation and distribution (Messick, 1993). By exclusively using item-based questions it is possible to favor this use of a simple equality-oriented heuristic. Factorial surveys allow researchers to avoid this problem. The first reason is that it requires respondents to make greater cognitive efforts than do item-based attitude measurements (Sauer et al., 2009, 2011). The vignettes presented have a more complex structure (several dimensions), and in most cases respondents are asked to evaluate several vignettes. Second, in a factorial survey respondents are provided with more information. The contexts of the evaluation can be compared in a way that is more appropriate to the subject; for example, when asked to evaluate the justice of earnings, individual factors such as performance and job experience may be complemented with contextual dimensions such as the economic situation of the company or the situation of the family (Sauer et al., 2009, 2011). In addition, it is likely that the use of realistic vignettes helps the respondents to imagine the situation better and thus enables them to make appropriate decisions that go beyond simple heuristics. For the measurement of income inequality this means that measurements that use factorial surveys should show significantly lower “inequality aversion” compared with classic item-based questions. This is suggested by the results of a population survey conducted in Germany in 2009 (Sauer et al., 2011). Of the 1,600 respondents recruited for an item- 5 Experimental behavioral economics operates in a similar way when distribution behavior in highly artificial game situations is used to draw conclusions about the justice preferences of participants, most of whom are students (cf. Fehr & Schmidt, 2006). 6 One example is an item respondents in the German General Social Survey (ALLBUS) are asked about on a regular basis to determine whether they agree with the statement “Income inequality in Germany is too high” (ALLBUS 2010, Item 6a), in order to draw conclusions about preferences of income inequalities in society. 5 based measurement, 91 percent stated that income inequality in Germany was “too high” or “far too high.” From these responses a clear equality preference can be derived. The same questionnaire also asked respondents to evaluate the justice of earnings of vignette persons. As Figure 2 shows, respondents clearly differentiated between just earnings depending on the occupation of the vignette individuals (Sauer et al., 2009), thus creating inequality with their judgments. Figure 2. Earnings rated as just and actual earnings by occupation of vignette individuals in Germany in 2009 Source: Attitudes toward justice from Sauer et al. (2009), actual earnings by occupation (mean of full-time-employed in a given occupation), calculated on the basis of SOEP 2009 The triangles connected by the continuous line in Figure 2 show the just earnings for each of the ten occupations (mean values), which were estimated on the basis of the respondents’ judgments, while the squares connected by the dashed line show the actual earnings of each of the occupations as given in the data set of the German Socio-Economic Panel 2009 (averages of full-time employees in each occupation [ISCO four-digit code]). The two lines run fairly parallel, which suggests that the respondents’ judgments were not arbitrary and that the estimations of just earnings based on the justice judgments provide meaningful values. On the whole, the respondents would slightly increase the earnings of individuals in lower-status occupations (manufacturing laborers, hairdressers) and lower the earnings of high-status occupations (medical doctors). However, the existing variation of earnings across occupations is still considered to be just. A uniform distribution of earnings—as could be derived as favored based on the item-based measurement—is not considered to be just. In addition, there is no statistically significant correlation between the inequality preference expressed in the vignette judgments and the preference for smaller inequalities in the item-based measurement. This means that if more detailed information about the potential recipients and their situation is available, the assessment of what constitutes just earnings is more differentiated, and that if this and other contextual information is not available, respondents use the “rule of thumb” 0 1000 2000 3000 4000 5000 6000 7000 8000 Just gross earnings Actual gross earnings 6 appropriate to the given situation and regard greater equality as just. This pattern is consistent with the findings on the use of the “equality heuristics” (see Messick, 1993; Roch et al., 2000). The potential of this method to allow for differentiated judgments of justice by using appropriate “contextualizations” has also been shown by two studies that do not focus explicitly on earnings. The first of these studies, Schaffer (1990), examined what criteria respondents used to determine what they thought would be fair child support payments the parent not living in the same household as their child should make. The results clearly showed a tendency toward justice judgments based on actual needs, with respondents stating that child support payments should be proportional to the income of the persons liable for child support. In other words, the higher the income of the parent liable for child support, the higher the child support payment should be to be considered just. The second study, Liebig and Mau (2002), focused on minimum social security and examined the attitudes toward a minimum income provided by the state. Their finding was that the respondents were generally in favor of a minimum level of social security that would ensure the recipients’ existence, which is consistent with the results of item-based measurements. However, their results also show that respondents think that the actual amount of welfare benefits should depend on whether the individuals described in the vignettes had put themselves in a state of welfare dependency. The general consensus what that those who are in financial distress through their own fault should receive less welfare state support than those who were in financial distress through no fault of their own. Thus, the preference for a uniform distribution is lower if additional information is provided on the potential recipients of an allocation. The above discussion suggests that factorial surveys are more useful in measuring attitudes toward justice that are not the result of routinized behavior in the form of applying an equality heuristic. Relative Importance: The Different Relevance of Individual Allocation Criteria The allocation criteria that underlie factual distribution processes often have different and, more important, competing normative implications. Normative conflicts therefore arise only as a result of the relative weighting of individual criteria, such as when considering the question of whether individuals’ formal education should be given more weight in determining their income than their seniority, their experience, or their actual job performance. Traditional item-based survey methods cannot clearly distinguish between individual determinants. Factorial surveys can make this distinction because the multifactorial design requires respondents to make “trade-offs” among various different dimensions and thus to weigh up individual characteristics against one another. This makes it possible to determine the influence of each named and varied attribute on the respondents’ response or judgment, as well as the relative importance of individual vignette dimensions. This may be done by considering standardized coefficients (Shepelak & Alwin, 1986) or by decomposing into the respective semi-partial explanation of variance (cf. Auspurg et al., 2013; Auspurg & Jäckle, 2012; Gatskova, 2013). Most of the existing research has investigated the relative importance of individual allocation criteria for individual incomes and household incomes, with a focus on two central questions. The first question is: Which of the individual characteristics of the income earners described in the vignettes and which of the situational factors are relevant for the justice evaluation? Here, the individual and situational characteristics are regarded as indicators of the general principles of justice described. The other central question is: Is it possible to identify differences among societies or among social groups? Generally speaking, the results of this research show that respondents actually weigh up several individual and situational factors against one another, and that they give the greatest relative weight to vignette dimensions that are directly related to employment (e.g., 7 Auspurg et al., 2013).7 Key factors in the decision making include occupation, human capital (education and experience), and individual performance: respondents believe that it would be just if the vignette individuals in more prestigious occupations who have more experience, a higher level of education, and above-average performance in the workplace earned more than others (Sauer et al., 2009). Thus, two distribution principles dominate in justice evaluations of earnings: first, the principle of proportionality as described in equity theory (Adams, 1965), because individual performance is seen as a central reward principle. Justice of earnings is constituted not by absolute equality but by proportional equality, that is, by the principle of equal pay for equal performance and unequal pay for unequal performance. Thus, contrary to the findings obtained by using the theoretical models advocated in behavioral economics (Fehr & Schmidt, 2006), individuals do not show “inequality aversion” when it comes to earnings; rather, it would be more accurate to say that they show “inequity aversion,” meaning that injustice is experienced, and is to be avoided, when individuals who have equal expenses achieve unequal outcomes or when individuals achieve equal outcomes with unequal expenses.8 However, because similar weight is given to the allocation category “occupation,” or prestige of the occupation, it is expected that for earnings to be considered just, they must also reflect differences in status. The results for Germany are shown in Figure 2; respondents make a clear differentiation of earnings by occupation (with factors such as level of education, performance, and experience used as control variables). A key observation in this respect is that respondents clearly expect that individuals in occupations with a higher social status and greater prestige should be entitled to a higher income, regardless of their current expenses and benefits.9 Thus, respondents believe that the allocation of income should be based on the principle of entitlement as well as on the proportionality principle. This finding is consistent with the results of a study Hermkens and Boerman (1989) conducted in the Netherlands which found that occupational prestige is the most important determinant for the level of just household income. 7 To compare the weight of individual dimensions in order to determine their relative weight, beta-coefficients (Alves & Rossi, 1978; Hermkens & Boerman, 1989), semi-partial explained variance (Auspurg et al., 2013; Gatskova, 2013), and t-values are considered (Liebig et al., 2010). 8 Incidentally, this inequity aversion has also been observed in non-human primates (see Brosnan, 2006). 9 The term “education” does not allow for a clear distinction because it can be understood not only as an indicator of individual productivity (proportionality principle) but also as a status characteristic (principle of entitlement). 8 Figure 3. A comparison of the relative importance of dimensions in vignette-based and item-based measurements Source: Liebig et al. (2010). The relative weight of the dimensions was measured using t-values. The fact that the studies considered here found that “status criteria” play an equally important role in the just allocation of income as “performance criteria” certainly also has to do with the differentiated form of the attitude measurement used in factorial surveys. If we compare the ranking of the different income criteria obtained directly using item-based survey with the ranking obtained indirectly using a factorial survey, the survey conducted in Germany in 2009 reveals significant differences. While the item-based survey leads to the conclusion that the proportionality principle is the most important criterion, factorial surveys show that the principle of entitlement (occupation) is the most important principle. The results also indicate that individual need is another important allocation criterion besides the two central principles of proportionality and entitlement: the number of children to be supported or marital status also constitute legitimate claims. Respondents think that individuals should be allocated a higher income if they have more family responsibilities, if they are the sole breadwinner, or if they have to support children. The above clearly shows that the evaluation of earnings is based on a combination and weighting of different principles of justice. This was the key assumption of the model proposed by Leventhal (1980): the justice of the earnings is evaluated on the basis of a combination of actual expenses (equity principle), position in the status and/or prestige structure of a society (principle of entitlement), and individual need (needs principle), with the last-mentioned principle given the least weight of all. The relative importance of the principles varies among different societies and among different social groups. This is not necessarily true of the role of the proportionality principle in the allocation of earnings (Auspurg et al., 2013; Cohn et al., 2000; Hysom & Fişek, 2011; Jasso & Meyersson Milgrom, 2008). A comparative study of Eastern European countries (Bulgaria, Hungary, Poland, Russia) and Western countries (France, Spain, United States) conducted by Cohn and colleagues (2000) found a clear preference for the equity principle in all of the countries under study. This finding is consistent with the results of a study of American and Turkish students 9 conducted by Hysom and Fişek (2011) and with those of a comparative study conducted by Jasso and Meyersson Milgrom (2008) in the United States and Sweden. Both of these studies showed that the preference for the equity principle was more pronounced among American respondents, whereas the Swedish respondents gave more weight to operational context conditions (industry, capital, location) in the allocation of earnings. Auspurg et al.’s (2013) comparative study of perceptions of income equity in Western Germany, Eastern Germany, and Ukraine found that age had a significant effect on performance orientation. Older respondents in Germany gave more weight to status criteria (principle of entitlement), whereas in Ukraine, older respondents gave more weight to the needs principle and younger respondents gave more weight to the performance principle. This serves to illustrate the third problem of attitudinal justice research, namely that different attitudes toward justice may be the result of different conditions of socialization (e.g., East vs. West) and different experiences with the processing of distributional conflicts. This will be the focus of the following section. Experience-Based Attitudes: Attitudes toward Justice and the Problem of Selective Sampling Many studies in the area of empirical justice research are based on laboratory experiments that use small and very homogeneous samples. These experiments involve surveys among students of psychology, economics, or the social sciences (e.g., Greenberg, 1993; Markovsky, 1988), which means that the results of these experiments are not necessarily generalizable. The same criticism leveled against all experimental studies—namely the problem of the external validity of results (Henrich et al., 2010; Jones, 2010)—can also be leveled against these experiments. However, in the field of justice attitude research, such criticism is much more problematic. There are theoretical reasons to believe (Liebig & Sauer, 2013; Vanberg, 2007), and there is empirical evidence that indicates (Almås et al., 2010; Keller et al., 2013; Meulemann & Birkelbach, 2001), that attitudes toward justice are not personality traits that remain stable and persistent through an individual’s life course. Thus, attitudes toward justice, and judgments of what is just, are “position effects” (Boudon, 1990) in that they reflect not only the specific interests but also the experiences individuals “accumulate” in different occupational and social positions over the life course (Liebig & Sauer, 2013, 2015). The local justice approach developed by Jon Elster in the 1990s (Elster, 1991a, 1991b, 1992) is explicitly based on this assumption. Owing to their experience in solving distribution problems, certain population groups have attitudes toward justice that are different from those of individuals who cannot draw on such experiences (Keller et al., 2013). This is particularly true of students because they are at a specific stage of their life course, have very similar sociostructural characteristics and social backgrounds, and little experience with social distribution conflicts and possible ways to resolve such conflicts. Experimental studies involving surveys among students thus capture only a small range of the spectrum of possible attitudes toward justice, namely the range of attitudes that are not based on working life experience and experience with the resolution of distribution conflicts. Thus, more than many other areas of research, justice research is faced with the challenge of finding ways to benefit from the advantages of experimental methods outside the laboratory and to examine heterogeneous populations. This is another problem factorial surveys can help overcome. Since they can be used to combine experimental methods and standardized surveys, factorial surveys can be embedded in traditional survey methods such as interviewer-based, online, or mail-based surveys (Sauer et al., 2009, 2011, 2014). One possible application is the determination of the weight of individual dimensions by individual groups of respondents. Such “cross-level interactions” have been observed by Schrenker (2009), who found that respondents with a high income gave significantly more weight to the income that vignette individuals had before reaching pension entitlement age when deciding what constitutes a just pension than did respondents with a low income. Auspurg et al. (2013) found that 10 respondents with a higher level of education gave more weight to occupational prestige when allocating earnings than did respondents with a lower level of education. Both of these examples show that justice judgments also reflect respondents’ personal interests and that experience with the resolution of distributional conflicts (or lack of it) plays a crucial role. This is supported by Buzea et al. (2013) and Gatskova (2013). Buzea et al. (2013) found significant differences between students and the rest of the population, with the former leaning more toward the equal-distribution principle. On the whole, the results reported here show that when larger segments of a population are to be surveyed, factorial surveys can help to overcome the problems that result from selective sampling and small sample size. Social Desirability: Justice as a Normative Concept Justice as a normative concept is always a part of normative discourses and of social conflicts that are covered by the media, especially when it comes to social problems of distribution (Brettschneider, 2007; Leisering, 2004; Volkmann, 2004). Attitudes toward justice that are related to such discourses are faced with the problem of socially desirable response behavior (Paulhus, 1984), meaning that respondents do not express what they really think or believe but instead respond in accordance with what they anticipate as the majority opinion or existing norms. Researchers find that this problem is particularly pronounced when conducting item-based surveys (King & Bruner, 2000) or relying on self-reports by individuals (Fisher & Katz, 2000). It is also one of the main problems in justice research. One example is the question of the pay gap between men and women. The general observation is that in item-based surveys, an individual’s gender should not be of any importance. Thus the general consensus is that gender-based wage discrimination— the so-called gender wage gap—is to be regarded as unjust. However, studies that use factorial surveys indicate that respondents do allocate different earnings to male and female workers and that they believe that men should earn more than women with otherwise identical characteristics. This finding was reported in one of the first studies to have used a factorial survey (i.e., Jasso & Rossi, 1977) and has been confirmed several times since (Auspurg et al., 2013; Jann, 2008; Jasso, 1994; Jasso & Webster, 1997, 1999; Sauer, 2014). The conclusion that can be drawn is that if several judgment-relevant dimensions are presented simultaneously, the tendency to give socially desirable responses—in this case, gender should not matter—is suppressed in the vignettes (Alexander & Becker, 1978; Mutz, 2011). Another example of the suppression of social-desirability effects by using factorial surveys is provided by a study on just taxation conducted by Liebig and Mau (2005), who used a regional sample in Germany to examine attitudes toward criteria of what respondents believed constituted a just tax system. They concluded that “most of the applicable principles of the current tax system are regarded as legitimate” (Liebig & Mau, 2005, p. 468, transl. from the German), that the principle of progressive taxation is generally regarded as just, but that “flat-tax” models were not consistent with the German respondents’ attitudes toward justice at the time the study was conducted. However, in the context of our own study, the difference between item-based and vignette-based surveys is more relevant. Respondents in an item-based survey were asked which of the dimensions presented should be relevant for taxation. “Marital status: Married” was one of the dimensions. The majority of respondents did not think that marital status should be considered as a dimension of taxation. The respondents were then asked to evaluate the rates of taxation of the fictitious taxpayers presented. “Married” was a level of the dimension “Marital status”—besides “cohabiting.” The results showed that the respondents thought it would be just to allocate a lower tax burden to the married fictitious taxpayers. Unlike in the item-based survey, which disregarded traditional ideas of marriage and family, in the vignette-based survey, the respondents lowered the tax burden on married vignette individuals. As before, there is good reason to believe that item- 11 based surveys tend to reflect a more socially desirable opinion. This is more evidence that factorial surveys are likely to help to avoid socially desirable response behavior (Auspurg et al., 2015). Causality: Scientific Explanation and Empirical Testing Empirical justice research that intends to provide not only mere descriptions of collective opinions and attitudes but also explanations on the basis of theoretically derived statements on causal connections is confronted with the same problem that all empirical social research has, namely that of modeling causal relationships and of sufficiently testing these relationships using empirical methods (Gangl, 2010; Opp, 2010). Traditional survey-based research, which uses cross-sectional data, is practically incapable of reliably identifying possible causal relationships, since correlations between two variables might just as well be caused by other variables that have not been measured. Due to the simultaneous measurement of theoretically assumed causes and effects, and due to the problem of unobserved heterogeneity, complex methods are needed to identify causal relationships post hoc (Gangl, 2010). Although longitudinal studies can be used to measure causes and effects separately in time, and appropriate methods (fixed-effects models) can be used to exclude the time- constant unobserved heterogeneity (Allison, 2009; Brüderl, 2010),10 the best way to test causal relationships is to use experimental methods (Falk & Heckman, 2009). The first reason is that the researcher can control the central independent variables (with causal effect) and that the experimental manipulations are randomly distributed among the participants (“randomization”). The second reason is that the laboratory allows for most confounding factors to be ruled out and thus for the isolated measurement of causal effects (Webster & Sell, 2007). However, it should be noted that the problems described above occur when specific populations are surveyed. Once again, factorial surveys can provide a way out of this dilemma. Ceteris paribus modeling of hypotheses enables direct testing of theoretical relationships, and the randomized assignment of vignettes to respondents ensures independence of vignette and respondent characteristics. This rules out third-variable effects. In the specific case of justice research this means that the survey instrument takes the context dependence of attitudes toward justice into consideration, given that the respondents are provided with an appropriate description of the allocation and distribution situation. In addition, random assignment makes it possible to test models that explain causal relationships (Liebig & Sauer, 2013, 2015). As this article has shown, factorial surveys can be used, if not to overcome the five key conceptual and methodological problems of attitude-based empirical research on justice entirely, then at least to reduce these problems to a certain extent. Conclusion In this paper, we discussed the reasons why factorial surveys are used in justice research, the specific methodological features of studies that use these surveys, and the key results such studies have provided in the past. Our findings confirm that an individual’s decision whether goods and burdens are allocated justly does indeed depend on certain characteristics of the recipients of such goods and burdens, as well as on situational conditions. Factorial surveys can help to reveal how respondents differentiate when judging whether something is just or not. Factorial survey studies also reveal consensus structures that relate to the application of the norms and principles that 10 There are some longitudinal studies in the area of justice research which use fixed-effect models, among others (cf. Liebig et al., 2012; Sauer & Valet, 2013; Schunck et al., 2013). 12 underlie them and in which not only specific cultural features but also specific sociopositional features play a role. A particular advantage of using factorial surveys is that they enable the determination of the exact amounts of specific rewards and burdens recipients would allocate. The studies on just earnings or household income, socially just welfare benefits, or fair taxation allow researchers to derive conclusions as to what a given society believes are equitable rewards and burdens. Factorial surveys thus have benefits that far exceed those of item-based surveys. Recent years have seen an increasing use of factorial surveys in empirical social research, as well as a growing number of studies that focus on the methodological issues of and the questions that arise in connection with this method. To the extent that the experiences and insights derived in this way will inform the practice of conducting factorial surveys, the conceptual and methodological approaches can be expected to be optimized further in the future. As regards justice research, the use of factorial surveys in international comparative studies appears to be particularly promising (e.g., Auspurg et al., 2013; Hysom & Fişek, 2011; Jasso & Meyersson Milgrom, 2008) because most of the research in this area has been descriptive in nature (cf. Liebig & Sauer, 2013, 2015) and for precisely this reason is incapable of identifying the causal mechanisms that underlie judgments in different societies and thus cannot clearly differentiate between cultural and positional influences. We also think that it would be worthwhile to continue to explore the potential of interactive survey methods. One question in justice research that has yet to be answered is what influence the distribution of earnings in a given society has on respondents’ assessments of their own earnings. Does the actual degree of income inequality have any influence at all, or do individuals usually evaluate their earnings without regard to societal distribution parameters? Factorial surveys may help to answer these questions because they offer the opportunity to vary distribution contexts and to test the causal effects of “structural” parameters on individual justice judgments. However, a question that remains largely unresolved is whether factorial surveys enable more reliable behavior predictions in the context of justice research (cf. Eifler, 2010). This is where we see the greatest potential for development in this research field. References Adams, J. S. (1965). Inequity in Social Exchange. Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 2, 267–299. Alexander, C. S., & Becker, H. J. (1978). The Use of Vignettes in Survey Research. Public Opinion Quarterly, 42(1), 93–104. Allison, P. D. (2009). Fixed Effects Regression Models. Thousand Oaks, CA; London; New Delhi; Singapore: SAGE. Almås, I., Cappelen, A. W., Sørensen, E. Ø., & Tungodden, B. (2010). Fairness and the Development of Inequality Acceptance. Science, 328(5982), 1176–1178. Alves, W. M., & Rossi, P. H. (1978). Who Should Get What? Fairness Judgments of the Distribution of Earnings. American Journal of Sociology, 84(3), 541–564. Auspurg, K., & Jäckle, A. (2012). First equals most important? Order effects in vignette-based measurement. ISER Working Paper Series, no. 2012-01. Colchester: Institute for Social and Economic Research. Auspurg, K., Gatskova, K., & Hinz, T. (2013). Vorstellungen von Lohngerechtigkeit in West- und Ostdeutschland und in der Ukraine. WSI-Mitteilungen, 66(2), 77–88. Auspurg, K., Hinz, T., & Sauer, C. (2013). Status Construction or Statistical Discrimination? New Insights on Fair Earnings from a Factorial Survey Study. Paper presented at the 108th Annual Meeting of the American Sociological Association, New York, NY. Auspurg, K., Hinz, T., Liebig, S., & Sauer, C. (2015). The Factorial Survey as a Method for Measuring Sensitive Issues. In U. Engel, B. Jann, P. Lynn, A. Scherpenzeel, & P. Sturgis 13 (Eds.), Improving Survey Methods: Lessons from Recent Research (pp. 137–150). New York, NY; Hove: Routledge. Beck, M., & Opp, K.-D. (2001). Der faktorielle Survey und die Messung von Normen. Kölner Zeitschrift für Soziologie und Sozialpsychologie, 53(2), 283–306. Boudon, R. (1990). Subjektive Rationalität und die Theorie der Ideologie. In H. Haferkamp (Ed.), Sozialstruktur und Kultur (pp. 384–414). Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. Brettschneider, A. (2007). Jenseits von Leistung und Bedarf: Zur Systematisierung sozialpolitischer Gerechtigkeitsdiskurse. Zeitschrift für Sozialreform, 53(4), 365–389. Brosnan, S. F. (2006). Nonhuman Species’ Reactions to Inequity and their Implications for Fairness. Social Justice Research, 19(2), 153–185. Brüderl, J. (2010). Kausalanalyse mit Paneldaten. In C. Wolf, & H. Best (Eds.), Handbuch der sozialwissenschaftlichen Datenanalyse (pp. 963–994). Wiesbaden: VS Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften/Springer Fachmedien. Buzea, C., Mesesan-Schmitz, L., & van de Vijver, F. J. R. (2013). Reward-Allocation Judgments in Romania: A Factorial Survey Approach. Revista de cercetare şi intervenţie socială, 40, 107–123. Cohn, E. S., White, S. O., & Sanders, J. (2000). Distributive and Procedural Justice in Seven Nations. Law and Human Behavior, 24(5), 553–579. Deutsch, M. (1985). Distributive Justice: A Social-Psychological Perspective. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Eifler, S. (2010). Validity of a Factorial Survey Approach to the Analysis of Criminal Behavior. Methodology: European Journal of Research Methods for the Behavioral and Social Sciences, 6(3), 139–146. Elster, J. (1991a). Local justice and interpersonal comparisons. In J. Elster, & J. E. Roemer (Eds.), Interpersonal Comparisons of Well-Being (pp. 98–126). Cambridge; New York, NY; Melbourne: Cambridge University Press. Elster, J. (1991b). Local justice: How institutions allocate scarce goods and necessary burdens. European Economic Review, 35(2–3), 273–291. Elster, J. (1992). Local justice: How Institutions Allocate Scarce Goods and Necessary Burdens. New York, NY: Russell Sage Foundation. Falk, A., & Heckman, J. J. (2009). Lab Experiments Are a Major Source of Knowledge in the Social Sciences. Science, 326(5952), 535–538. Fehr, E., & Schmidt, K. M. (2006). The Economics of Fairness, Reciprocity and Altruism – Experimental Evidence and New Theories. In S.-C. Kolm, & J. M. Ythier (Eds.), Handbook of the Economics of Giving, Altruism and Reciprocity: Volume 1: Foundations (pp. 615– 691). Amsterdam; Oxford: North-Holland. Fisher, R. J., & Katz, J. E. (2000). Social-desirability bias and the validity of self-reported values. Psychology and Marketing, 17(2), 105–120. Gangl, M. (2010). Causal Inference in Sociological Research. Annual Review of Sociology, 36(1), 21–47. Gatskova, K. (2013). Distributive justice attitudes in Ukraine: Need, desert or social minimum? Communist and Post-Communist Studies, 46(2), 227–241. Greenberg, J. (1993). Stealing in the Name of Justice: Informational and Interpersonal Moderators of Theft Reactions to Underpayment Inequity. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 54(1), 81–103. Hegtvedt, K. A. (2006). Justice Frameworks. In P. J. Burke (Ed.), Contemporary Social Psychological Theories (pp. 46–69). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Henrich, J., Heine, S. J., & Norenzayan, A. (2010). The weirdest people in the world? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 33(2–3), 61–83. Hermkens, P. J., & Boerman, F. (1989). Consensus With Respect to the Fairness of Incomes: Differences Between Social Groups. Social Justice Research, 3(3), 201–215. 14 Hysom, S. J., & Fişek, M. H. (2011). Situational determinants of reward allocation: The equity– equality equilibrium model. Social Science Research, 40(4), 1263–1285. Jann, B. (2008). Lohngerechtigkeit und Geschlechterdiskriminierung: Evidenz aus einem Vignetten-Experiment. In B. Jann (Ed.), Erwerbsarbeit, Einkommen und Geschlecht: Studien zum Schweizer Arbeitsmarkt (pp. 107–126). Wiesbaden: VS Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften. Jasso, G. (1978). On the Justice of Earnings: A New Specification of the Justice Evaluation Function. American Journal of Sociology, 83(6), 1398–1419. Jasso, G. (1980). A New Theory of Distributive Justice. American Sociological Review, 45(1), 3– 32. Jasso, G. (1994). Assessing Individual and Group Differences in the Sense of Justice: Framework and Application to Gender Differences in the Justice of Earnings. Social Science Research, 23(4), 368–406. Jasso, G. (2006). Factorial Survey Methods for Studying Beliefs and Judgments. Sociological Methods & Research, 34(3), 334–423. Jasso, G. (2007). Studying Justice: Measurement, Estimation, and Analysis of the Actual Reward and the Just Reward. In K. Törnblom, & R. Vermunt (Eds.), Distributive and Procedural Justice: Research and Social Applications (pp. 225–253). London; Burlington, VT: Ashgate. Jasso, G., & Meyersson Milgrom, E. M. (2008). Distributive Justice and CEO Compensation. Acta Sociologica, 51(2), 123–143. Jasso, G., & Rossi, P. H. (1977). Distributive Justice and Earned Income. American Sociological Review, 42(4), 639–651. Jasso, G., & Webster, M. J. (1997). Double Standards in Just Earnings for Male and Female Workers. Social Psychology Quarterly, 60(1), 66–78. Jasso, G., & Webster, M. J. (1999). Assessing the Gender Gap in Just Earnings and Its Underlying Mechanisms. Social Psychology Quarterly, 62(4), 367–380. Jasso, G., & Wegener, B. (1997). Methods for Empirical Justice Analysis: Part 1. Framework, Models, and Quantities. Social Justice Research, 10(4), 393–430. Jones, D. (2010). A WEIRD View of Human Nature Skews Psychologists’ Studies. Science, 328(5986), 1627. Keller, M., Gummerum, M., Canz, T., Gigerenzer, G., & Takezawa, M. (2013). The Is And Ought of Sharing: The Equality Heuristic Across The Lifespan. In R. Hertwig, U. Hoffrage, & ABC Research Group (Eds.), Simple Heuristics in a Social World (pp. 171–198). New York, NY: Oxford University Press. King, M. F., & Bruner, G. C. (2000). Social desirability bias: A neglected aspect of validity testing. Psychology and Marketing, 17(2), 79–103. Leisering, L. (2004). Paradigmen sozialer Gerechtigkeit: Normative Diskurse im Umbau des Sozialstaats. In S. Liebig, H. Lengfeld & S. Mau (Eds.), Verteilungsprobleme und Gerechtigkeit in modernen Gesellschaften (pp. 29–68). Frankfurt am Main: Campus. Leventhal, G. S. (1980). What Should Be Done With Equity Theory? New Approaches to the Study of Fairness in Social Relationships. In K. J. Gergen, M. S. Greenberg, & R. H. Willis (Eds.), Social Exchange: Advances in Theory and Research (pp. 27–55). New York, NY: Plenum Press. Liebig, S., & Mau, S. (2002). Einstellungen zur sozialen Mindestsicherung: Ein Vorschlag zur differenzierten Erfassung normativer Urteile. Kölner Zeitschrift für Soziologie und Sozialpsychologie, 54(1), 109–134. Liebig, S., & Mau, S. (2005). Wann ist ein Steuersystem gerecht? Einstellungen zu allgemeinen Prinzipien der Besteuerung und zur Gerechtigkeit der eigenen Steuerlast. Zeitschrift für Soziologie, 34(6), 468–491. Liebig, S., & Sauer, C. (2013). Soziologische Gerechtigkeitsanalyse: Überlegungen zur theoretischen Fundierung eines Forschungsfeldes. Analyse und Kritik, 35(2), 371–394. 15 Liebig, S., & Sauer, C. (2015). Sociology of Justice. In C. Sabbagh & M. Schmitt (Eds.), Handbook of Social Justice Theory and Research. New York: Springer. Liebig, S., Sauer, C., & Schupp, J. (2012). The justice of earnings in dual-earner households. Research in Social Stratification and Mobility, 30(2), 219–232. Liebig, S., Sauer, C., May, M., Hinz, T., Auspurg, K., Joos, A., & Schwarz, J. (2010). Bericht zur Studie Einkommensgerechtigkeit in Deutschland. Bielefeld: Bielefeld University/Konstanz: University of Konstanz. Markovsky, B. (1988). Injustice and Arousal. Social Justice Research, 2(3), 223–233. Markovsky, B., & Eriksson, K. (2012). Comparing Direct and Indirect Measures of Just Rewards. Sociological Methods & Research, 41(1), 199–216. Messick, D. M. (1993). Equality as a decision heuristic. In B. A. Mellers, & J. Baron (Eds.), Psychological Perspectives on Justice: Theory and Applications (pp. 11–31). Cambridge; New York, NY; Oakleigh, Vic.: Cambridge University Press. Meulemann, H., & Birkelbach, K. (2001). Biographische Erfahrungen und politische Einstellungen zwischen Jugend und Lebensmitte: Die Entwicklung von Wertansprüchen an die Politik bei ehemaligen Gymnasiasten im 16., 30. und 43. Lebensjahr zwischen 1969 – 1997. Politische Vierteljahresschrift, 42(1), 30–50. Mutz, D. C. (2011). Population-Based Survey Experiments. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Opp, K.-D. (2010). Kausalität als Gegenstand der Sozialwissenschaften und der multivariaten Statistik. In C. Wolf, & H. Best (Eds.), Handbuch der sozialwissenschaftlichen Datenanalyse (pp. 9–38). Wiesbaden: VS Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften/Springer Fachmedien. Paulhus, D. L. (1984). Two-component models of socially desirable responding. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 46(3), 598–609. Rawls, J. (1975). Eine Theorie der Gerechtigkeit. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. Roch, S. G., Lane, J. A. S., Samuelson, C. D., Allison, S. T., & Dent, J. L. (2000). Cognitive Load and the Equality Heuristic: A Two-Stage Model of Resource Overconsumption in Small Groups. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 83(2), 185–212. Rossi, P. H., & Anderson, B. (1982). The factorial survey approach: an introduction. In P. H. Rossi, & S. L. Nock (Eds.), Measuring Social Judgements: The Factorial Survey Approach (pp. 15–67). Beverly Hills, CA: Sage. Runciman, W. G. (1966). Relative Deprivation and Social Justice: A Study of Attitudes to Social Inequality in Twentieth-Century England. London: Routledge. Sauer, C. (2014). A Just Gender Pay Gap? Three Factorial Survey Studies On Justice Evaluations Of Earnings for Male and Female Employees. SFB 882 Working Paper Series, no. 29. Bielefeld: DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities. Sauer, C., Auspurg, K., Hinz, T., & Liebig, S. (2011). The Application of Factorial Surveys in General Population Samples: The Effects of Respondent Age and Education on Response Times and Response Consistency. Survey Research Methods, 5(3), 89–102. Sauer, C., Auspurg, K., Hinz, T., Liebig, S., & Schupp, J. (2009). Die Bewertung von Erwerbseinkommen – Methodische und inhaltliche Analysen zu einer Vignettenstudie im Rahmen des SOEP-Pretest 2008. SOEPpapers on Multidisciplinary Panel Data Research, no. 189. Berlin: DIW Berlin, The German Socio-Economic Panel (SOEP). Sauer, C., Auspurg, K., Hinz, T., Liebig, S., & Schupp, J. (2014). Method Effects in Factorial Surveys: An Analysis of Respondents’ Comments, Interviewers’ Assessments, and Response Behavior. SOEPpapers on Multidisciplinary Panel Data Research, no. 629 Berlin: DIW Berlin, The German Socio-Economic Panel (SOEP). Sauer, C., & Valet, P. (2013). Less is Sometimes More: Consequences of Overpayment on Job Satisfaction and Absenteeism. Social Justice Research, 26(2), 132–150. Schaeffer, N. C. (1990). Principles of Justice in Judgments About Child Support. Social Forces, 69(1), 157–179. 16 Schrenker, M. (2009). Warum fast alle das deutsche Rentensystem ungerecht finden, aber trotzdem nichts daran ändern möchten: Die Wahrnehmung gerechter Renten und die Akzeptanz von Rentenreformen. Kölner Zeitschrift für Soziologie und Sozialpsychologie, 61(2), 259–282. Schunck, R., Sauer, C., & Valet, P. (2013). Macht Ungerechtigkeit krank? Gesundheitliche Folgen von Einkommens(un)gerechtigkeit. WSI-Mitteilungen, 66(8), 553–561. Shepelak, N. J., & Alwin, D. F. (1986). Beliefs about Inequality and Perceptions of Distributive Justice. American Sociological Review, 51(1), 30–46. Törnblom, K. Y. (1992). The social psychology of distributive justice. In K. R. Scherer (Ed.), Justice: Interdisciplinary Perspectives (pp. 177–236). Cambridge; New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. Vanberg, V. J. (2007). Marktwirtschaft und Gerechtigkeit – Idee und Kritik der sozialen Gerechtigkeit im Konzept der Sozialen Marktwirtschaft. In S. Empter, & R. B. Vehrkamp (Eds.), Soziale Gerechtigkeit – eine Bestandsaufnahme (pp. 25–50). Gütersloh: Bertelsmann-Stiftung. Volkmann, U. (2004). Die journalistische Konstruktion gerechter Ungleichheiten. In S. Liebig, H. Lengfeld, & S. Mau (Eds.), Verteilungsprobleme und Gerechtigkeit in modernen Gesellschaften (pp. 297–328). Frankfurt am Main: Campus. Wallander, L. (2009). 25 years of factorial surveys in sociology: A review. Social Science Research, 38(3), 505–520. Webster, M., & Sell, J. (2007). Theory and Experimentation in the Social Sciences. In W. Outhwaite, & S. Turner (Eds.), The SAGE Handbook of Social Science Methodology (pp. 190–207). London; Thousand Oaks, CA; New Delhi; Singapore: SAGE. Wegener, B. (1987). The illusion of distributive justice. European Sociological Review, 3(1), 1–13. 17 1 Appendix Table 1. Distributive justice: An overview of factorial surveys Note: Publications have been selected on the basis of the procedure described in Footnote 3. Jasso and Rossi (1977), Jasso (1994), and Jasso & Webster (1997) are based on the same sample. NV = Number of vignettes used; NB = Number of respondents; NV/NB = Number of vignettes per respondent; ? = Exact number not reported. The column “Dimensions” is read as follows: e.g., 5 (2 × 34) means 5 dimensions with 1 × 2 levels and 4 × 3 levels. Sorted by topic and year. Characteristics that were used as dependent variables, had no influence, or were not examined in the article are given in brackets. Reference Object of investigation Relevant characteristics Dimensions (levels) NB NV NV/NB Answering scale Vignette sampling Respondent population Analysis Countries Alves & Rossi (1978) Earned income (individual) Earned Income, Occupational Status, Marital Status, Number of Children, Education, Taxation; [Gender], [Ethnicity] 8 (52 × 2 × 4 × 7 × ? × ? × ? × ?) 522 ? 50 9-point scale Random General population OLS regression USA Jasso (1994) Earned income (individual) Gender; [Relational Status], [Earned Income], [Education], [Number of Children], [Occupational Status] 6 (2² × 7 × 10 × 99 × 15) 200 600 60 9-point scale Random General population Two-stage estimation procedure USA Jasso &Webster (1997) Earned income (individual) Gender; [Relational Status], [Earned Income], [Education], [Number of Children], [Occupational Status] 6 (2² × 7 × 10 × 99 × 15) 200 100 60 9-point scale Random General population OLS regression USA Jasso & Webster (1999) Earned income (individual) Age, Education, Gender, Earned Income; [Occupational Status] 5 (2 × 10² × 4 × 15) 377 30 10 Magnitude scale Random Students Robust regression, respondent- specific regression, and vignette-specific regression USA Cohn et al. (2000) Earned income (individual) Effort (Certificate of Employment, Willingness to Accept Occupational Changes/Salary Cuts), Need (Labor Market Situation, Marital Status); [Voice], [Impartiality of the Company] 4 (42); 5 (5²) 831; 786; 824; 765; 762; 775; 810 32; 1000 2 10-point scale Complete design; random General population OLS regression Bulgaria, Hungary, Poland, Russia, France, Spain, USA 18 Jann (2008) Earned income (individual) Gender, Need (Single Parent, Narrow Finances), Effort (Engagement, Complies with Performance Requirements) 3 (3³) 531 8 1 11-point scale Complete design General population OLS regression Switzerland Jasso & Meyersson Milgrom (2008) Earned income (individual) Age, Gender, Job Experience, Company Site, Industrial Sector, Education, Financial Assets of the Company; [Earned Income] 8 (11 × 2 × 15 × 16× 3 × 4 × 272) 47; 36 80 40 Magnitude scale Random Students Multilevel models and respondent- specific regression USA, Sweden Sauer et al. (2009) Earned income (individual) Earned Income, Occupational Status, Education, Effort, Marital Status, Number of Children, Gender, Situation of the Company, Company Size; [Age] 10 (2 × 35 × 4 × 5 × 10²) 1066 240 24 Magnitude scale Fractionalized design General population Robust regression Germany Hysom & Fişek (2011) Earned income (individual) Kind of Task, Co-Worker Relations, Kind of Occupation; [Gender], [Occupational Status], [Age], [Education], [Occupational Experience], [Group Size] 9 (24 × 35) 295; 314 8 8 Allocation of relative proportion of the reward Selective choice of vignette dimensions on the basis of pretests Students OLS regression USA, Turkey Auspurg et al. (2013) Earned income (individual) Germany (West): Occupational Status, Effort, Education, Marital Status, Gender, Age, Number of Children; [Situation of the Company], [Form of Company], [Earned Income] Germany (East): Occupational Status, Effort, Education, Marital Status, Number of Children, Age, Gender; [Situation of the Company], [Form of Company], [Earned Income] Ukraine: Number of Children, Effort, Occupational Status, Marital Status, Gender, Education, Age; [Situation of the Company], [Form of the Company], [Earned Income] 10 (Germany: 4 × 2 × 35 × 10² × 5; Ukraine: 4 × 2² × 34 × 10² × 5) 944; 1797 240 24 100-point scale Fractionalized design General population Robust regression Germany, Ukraine Buzea et al. (2013) Earned income (individual) Contribution, Occupational Experience, Familiarity with the task, Need (Number of Children), Future Interactions, Age; [Gender] 7 (2 × 8 × 35) 200 8000 40 Percentage pay increase Random Students Multilevel models Romania 19 Gatskova (2013) Earned income (individual) Older Generation: Number of Children, Effort, Occupational Status, Relational Status, Gender, Form of the Company, Age; [Education], [Earned Income], [Financial Situation of the Company] Younger Generation: Number of Children, Effort, Occupational Status, Gender, Relational Status, Form of the Company, Age; [Education], [Earned Income], [Financial Situation of the Company] 10 (2 × 36 × 6 × 10²) 12 11-point scale Fractionalized design General population Robust regression Ukraine Jasso & Rossi (1977) Earned income (household) Multiple Person Households: Education (Husband), Occupational Status (Husband & Wife), Marital Status, Family Income; [Education (Wife)], [Number of Children] Multiple Person Households: Gender, Relational Status, Earned Income, Education, Number of Children, Occupational Status 6 (2² × 7 × 10 × 99 × 15) 200 600 60 9-point scale Random General population OLS regression USA Shepelak & Alwin (1986) Earned income (household) Single Households: Ethnicity, Education, Size of Family, Vocational Training, Gender, Occupational Prestige Family Household: Education (Husband & Wife), Vocational Training, Gender, Occupational Status of Husband & Wife; [Family Size] 6 328 135 15 Monetary units Selective choice General population OLS regression USA Hermkens & Boerman (1989) Earned income (household) Occupational Status, Number of Employed Persons in Household, Number of Children, Occupational Effort; [Gender], [Age] 6 (2² × 27 × 50 × ? × ?) 795 4200; 8400 5; 10 Monetary units Random General population OLS regression Netherlands Schaeffer (1990) Child support Earned Income Father, Earned Income Mother, Marital Status Father, Marital Status Mother, 6 (23 × 32 × 5) 1003 3 Monetary units Random General population Tobit regression USA 20 Number of Children [Occupational Status Father] Liebig & Mau (2002) Minimum collateral Number of Children, Occupational Status, Age, Occupational Position, Amount of State Transfers; [Reason for Lay-Off], [Amount of Income Supplement], [Gender] 8 (22 × 32 × 1 × 4 × 6 × 5) 121 48 24 Magnitude scale Random General population Robust regression Germany Liebig & Mau (2005) Taxes Earned Income, Number of Children, Amount of Inheritance, Marital Status; [Social Engagement], [Age], [Gender], [Occupational Status] 8 (2² × 3 × 4² × 5 × 19 × 33 ) 586 20 20 Magnitude scale Random General population Robust regression Germany Schrenker (2009) Pensions Amount of last Income, Years of Professional Experience, Number of Children, Combined Supply of Partner, Gender; [Amount of Monthly Pension] 6 (22 × 11 × 5 × 6 × 10) 2690 250 25 Monetary units and 11- point scale Random General population Random coefficient models and OLS models (including beta- values and t- values) Germany 21 Previously published SFB 882 Working Papers: Diewald, Martin / Faist, Thomas (2011): From Heterogeneities to Inequalities: Looking at Social Mechanisms as an Explanatory Approach to the Generation of Social Inequalities, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 1, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Bielefeld. Busch, Anne (2011): Determinants of Occupational Gender Segregation: Work Values and Gender (A)Typical Occupational Preferences of Adolescents, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 2, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A3, Bielefeld. Faist, Thomas (2011): Multiculturalism: From Heterogeneities to Social (In)Equalities, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 3, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project C3, Bielefeld. Amelina, Anna (2012): Jenseits des Homogenitätsmodells der Kultur: Zur Analyse von Transnationalität und kulturellen Interferenzen auf der Grundlage der hermeneutischen Wissenssoziologie, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 4, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project C3, Bielefeld. Osmanowski, Magdalena / Cardona, Andrés (2012): Resource Dilution or Resource Augmentation? Number of Siblings, Birth Order, Sex of the Child and Frequency of Mother’s Activities with Preschool Children, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 5, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A1, Bielefeld. Amelina, Anna / Bilecen, Başak / Barglowski, Karolina / Faist, Thomas (2012): Ties That Protect? The Significance of Transnationality for the Distribution of Informal Social Protection in Migrant Networks, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 6, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project C3, Bielefeld. Alemann, Annette von / Beaufaÿs, Sandra / Reimer, Thordis (2012): Gaining Access to the Field of Work Organizations with the Issue of “Work-Family-Life Balance” for Fathers, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 7, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project B5, Bielefeld. Kaiser, Till (2012): Haben gebildetere Mütter gewissenhaftere Kinder? Soziale Herkunft und Persönlichkeitsentwicklung im frühkindlichen Alter, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 8, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A1, Bielefeld. Gusy, Christoph / Müller, Sebastian (2012): Social Construction of Heterogeneity Indicators and their Relationship to Law. The Example of Guiding Principles in Immigration Law, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 9, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project C4, Bielefeld. Liebig, Stefan / May, Meike / Sauer, Carsten / Schneider, Simone / Valet, Peter (2012): Inequality Preferences in Interviewer- and Self-Administered Interviews, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 10, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A6, Bielefeld. Fauser, Margit / Voigtländer, Sven / Tuncer, Hidayet / Liebau, Elisabeth / Faist, Thomas / Razum, Oliver (2012): Transnationality and Social Inequalities of Migrants in Germany, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 11, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project C1, Bielefeld. Freistein, Katja / Koch, Martin (2012): Global Inequality and Development. Textual Representations of the World Bank and UNDP, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 12, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project C5, Bielefeld. Golsch, Katrin (2013): Shall I Help You My Dear? Examining Variations in Social Support for Career Advancement within Partnerships, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 13, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A3, Bielefeld. Bröckel, Miriam / Busch, Anne / Golsch, Katrin (2013): Headwind or Tailwind – Do Partner’s Resources Support or Restrict a Promotion to a Leadership Position in Germany?, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 14, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A3, Bielefeld. Cardona, Andrés (2013): Closing the Group or the Market? The Two Sides of Weber’s Concept of Closure and Their Relevance for the Study of Intergroup Inequality, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 15, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A1, Bielefeld. Friedhoff, Stefan / Meier zu Verl, Christian / Pietsch, Christian / Meyer, Christian / Vompras, Johanna / Liebig, Stefan (2013): Social Research Data. Documentation, Management, and Technical Implementation at SFB 882, SFB 882 Working Paper Series, No. 16, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Project “Information and Data Infrastructure” (INF), Bielefeld. Reinecke, Jost / Stemmler, Mark / Sünkel, Zara / Schepers, Deborah / Weiss, Maren / Arnis, Maria / Meinert, Julia / Kucur-Uysal, Burcu / Pöge, Andreas / Wallner, Susanne / Wittenberg, Jochen (2013): The Development of Deviant and Delinquent Behavior over the Life Course in the Context of Processes of Social Inequalities, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 17, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A2, Bielefeld. Hense, Andrea / Edler, Susanne / Liebig, Stefan (2013): Individual Determinants of Recalls, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 18, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project B4, Bielefeld. Bilecen, Başak (2013): Analyzing Informal Social Protection Across Borders: Synthesizing Social Network Analysis with Qualitative Interviews, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 19, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project C3, Bielefeld. Schunck, Reinhard / Abendroth, Anja-Kristin / Diewald, Martin / Melzer, Silvia Maja / Pausch, Stephanie (2013): What do Women and Men Want? Investigating and Measuring Preference Heterogeneity for Life Outcomes using a Factorial Survey, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 20, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project B3, Bielefeld. Sauer, Carsten / Valet, Peter / Liebig, Stefan (2013): The Impact of Within and Between Occupational Inequalities on People’s Justice Perceptions Towards their Own Earnings, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 21, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A6, Bielefeld. Schneider, Simone / Valet, Peter (2013): Social Comparison Orientations and their Consequences for Justice Perceptions of Earnings, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 22, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A6, Bielefeld. Cardona, Andrés (2013): The Programmatic Bias in the Discussion on Social Mechanisms in Sociology, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 23, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A1, Bielefeld. Hille, Adrian / Schupp, Jürgen (2013): How Learning a Musical Instrument Affects the Development of Skills, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 24, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A1, Bielefeld. Faist, Thomas (2014): "We are all Transnationals now": The Relevance of Transnationality for Understanding Social Inequalities, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 25, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project C1, Bielefeld. Lohmann, Henning / Ferger, Florian (2014): Educational Poverty in a Comparative Perspective: Theoretical and Empirical Implications, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 26, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A5, Bielefeld. Freistein, Katja / Koch, Martin (2014): The Effects of Measuring Poverty – Indicators of the World Bank, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 27, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project C5, Bielefeld. Andernach, Björn / Schunck, Reinhard (2014): Investigating the Feasibility of a Factorial Survey in a CATI, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 28, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project B3, Bielefeld. Sauer, Carsten (2014): A Just Gender Pay Gap? Three Factorial Survey Studies on Justice Evaluations of Earnings for Male and Female Employees, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 29, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A6, Bielefeld. Berger, Johannes (2014): Dringend erforderlich: eine stärker vereinheitlichte soziologische Ungleichheitsforschung, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 30, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project Z, Bielefeld. Karsch, Anna (2014): Geschlechtstypische Unterschiede in den Berufspräferenzen deutscher Jugendlicher, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 31, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A3, Bielefeld. Barglowski, Karolina (2014): Social Classifications and Inequalities: Ideologies of Mobility, Care and Work in Transnational Families, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 32, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project C3, Bielefeld. Sauer, Carsten / Valet, Peter / Liebig, Stefan (2014): Ungleichheiten am Arbeitsmarkt und die Gerechtigkeitswahrnehmung von Erwerbseinkommen, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 33, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A6, Bielefeld. Dawid, Herbert / Harting, Philipp / Neugart, Michael (2014): Cohesion Policy and Inequality Dynamics: Insights from a Heterogeneous Agents Macroeconomic Model, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 34, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A4, Bielefeld. Liebig, Stefan / May, Meike / Sauer, Carsten / Schneider, Simone / Peter Valet (2014): The Effect of Interviewer Presence on Inequality Preferences, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 35, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A6, Bielefeld. Cardona, Andrés / Diewald, Martin (2014): Opening the Black Box of Primary Effects: Relative Risk Aversion and Maternal Time Investments in Preschool Children, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 36, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A1, Bielefeld. Fehl, Caroline / Freistein, Katja (2014): Institutional Mechanisms of Global Inequality Reproduction, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 37, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project C5, Bielefeld. Freistein, Katja (2014): Are there any Global Imaginaries of Equality and Democracy in Discussions about Inequality? SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 38, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project C5, Bielefeld. Meinert, Julia (2014): Selection into criminogenic contexts by personal heterogeneity and its effects on delinquency, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 39, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A2, Bielefeld. Schepers, Debbie (2014): Social Inequalities as Causes of the Causes of Juvenile Delinquency. Heterogeneities in the Context of Situational Action Theory, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 40, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A2, Bielefeld. Abendroth, Anja-Kristin / Pausch, Stephanie / Böhm, Sebastian (2014): German Fathers and Their Preference to Reduce Working Hours to Care for Their Children, SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 41, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A3, Bielefeld. Bürmann, Marvin: Determinanten beruflichen Aufstiegs (2014): Der Einfluss von Unterstützung durch Kollegen und Vorgesetzte. Eine Sekundäranalyse anhand der Daten des Sozio-oekonomischen Panels. SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 42, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A3, Bielefeld. Rosenbohm, Sophie / Gebel, Tobias / Hense, Andrea (2015): Potenziale und Voraussetzungen für die Sekundäranalyse qualitativer Interviewdaten in der Organisationsforschung. SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 43, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project B4/INF, Bielefeld. Schneider, Simone / Shamon, Hawal (2015): How Others' Earnings influence our Justice Perceptions. Studying the Effects of Income Distribution and Social Position on Reflexive Justice Evaluations among German Employees. SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 44, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A6, Bielefeld. Kruphölter, Sonja / Sauer, Carsten / Valet, Peter (2015): Occupational gender segregation and gender differences in justice evaluations. SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 45, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A6, Bielefeld. Liebig, Stefan / Sauer, Carsten / Hülle, Sebastian (2015): Why is justice regarded as so important? Theoretical considerations and an empirical test of a fundamental question. SFB 882 Working Paper Series No. 46, DFG Research Center (SFB) 882 From Heterogeneities to Inequalities, Research Project A6, Bielefeld. Foliennummer 1 Liebig-Sauer-Friedhoff-2015.pdf Introduction Contextual Information: Complexity of Distribution Processes Conclusion References 1 Appendix 10-point scale work_e2yhm5n3vjayjoktid3w3h6d6m ---- Juvenile Justice in Mexico Laws 2014, 3, 580–597; doi:10.3390/laws3030580 laws ISSN 2075-471X www.mdpi.com/journal/laws/ Article Juvenile Justice in Mexico Martha Frías Armenta * and Livier Gómez Martínez Department of Law, Universidad de Sonora, Rosales y Transversal s/n Col, Centro, Hermosillo, Sonora 83246, Mexico; E-Mail: liv_gomez@hotmail.com * Author to whom correspondence should be addressed; E-Mail: marthafrias@sociales.uson.mx; Tel.: +52-662-259-2170; Fax: +52-662-259-2171. Received: 18 July 2014; in revised form: 15 August 2014 / Accepted: 18 August 2014 / Published: 26 August 2014 Abstract: The first tribunal in Mexico was established in the central state of San Luis Potosi in 1926. The Law Regarding Social Prevention and Juvenile Delinquency for the Federal District and Mexican territories was promulgated in 1928. In 2005, Article 18 of the Mexican Constitution was modified to establish a comprehensive system (“Sistema Integral de justicia” in Spanish) of justice for juveniles between 12 and 18 years old who had committed a crime punishable under criminal law. Its objective was to guarantee juveniles all the due process rights established for adults, in addition to the special ones recognized for minors. The constitutional reform also provides a framework that includes special tribunals as well as alternative justice options for juveniles. With these reforms, institutionalization of minors was to be considered an extreme measure applicable only to felonies and to juveniles older than 14. In 2006, all states within the Mexican federation enacted the “Law of justice for adolescents”. This system, at both the federal and state levels, formalizes a new global paradigm with regard to the triangular relationship between children, the State and the Law. It recognizes that children are also bearers of the inherent human rights recognized for all individuals, instead of simply objects in need of protection. However, despite formally aligning Mexican juvenile justice law with the Convention on the Rights of the Child (CRC), issues of actual substantive rights remained and new ones have appeared. For example, juveniles younger than 14 who have not committed a felony are released from institutions without any rehabilitation or treatment options, and alternative forms of justice were included without evaluating their possibilities of application or their conditions for success. In addition, the economic status of most juvenile detainees continues to be one of the most important determining factors in the administration of justice. Juveniles lack real access to an adequate defense because they OPEN ACCESS Laws 2014, 3 581 cannot afford to pay lawyers. This disconnection between rights and reality undermines the new system, raising the question of whether recent modifications to bring laws in line with international norms are in fact advancing juvenile justice. By approaching the Mexican juvenile justice systems as a single, multilayered system combining international, federal and local laws and procedures, we can better describe some of the substantive inconsistencies that continue to prevail, even as new ones develop in terms of children’s rights. Keywords: juvenile delinquency; justice; Mexico 1. Introduction The development of juvenile justice law in Mexico was directed to create special tribunals and laws for juveniles, keeping them separate from criminal laws, processes and penalties administered to adults. Two objectives were paramount: juveniles should be separated from adults so as not to be negatively influenced by them, and should be treated differently from adults. This “special treatment” was based on principles of education and protection [1]. The first tribunal in Mexico was established in the central state of San Luis Potosi in 1926. However, the subsequent legal developments in the area of juvenile justice occurred mainly in Mexico City. Those first courts adopted the model of the Chicago Court and of the Paternal Judge of New York [2]. The Law regarding Social Prevention and Juvenile Delinquency for the Federal District and Mexican territories was stated in 1928 [2]. It regulated juvenile offenses for common matters in the Federal District and for federal matters in the rest of the country. This law established that minors under 15 years old do not incur criminal responsibility. Therefore, they could not be criminally prosecuted nor submitted to judicial process. However, it decreed that these minors should be placed under state protection, which should take the appropriate actions in order to educate them [3]. Moreover, the tribunal action was extended to cases of neglected (abandoned), undisciplined, and vagrant children. In 1941, the Organic Law and Procedural Norms for Minors Tribunal and its Auxiliary Institutions for the Federal District and Territories was passed, modifying the structure of juvenile courts [4]. That law decreed two courts for Mexico City, with three members each, who would take decisions in a plenary session [5]. Article 18 of the Mexican Constitution was amended in 1964 to expressly recognize juvenile delinquents [6]. It mandated the federal government and the state governments to establish special institutions for the treatment of juvenile delinquents. After the first national conference for juvenile offenders in 1973, a new theory for treatment emerged and the law was changed once more [2]. In 1974, the law creating the Juvenile Tutelary Council in Federal Territories and the Federal District was passed [7]. This law included new concepts, objectives and procedures, and returned to preventive, protectionist, corrective and non-punitive treatment. The tribunal was divided into small courts and its structure included a president and a counselor for each president. This law served as a model for similar legislation in other states of the republic. The fundamental characteristic of the tutelary approach is that minors are not considered Laws 2014, 3 582 criminals. Accordingly, in this law there is no criminal responsibility, because due their age, juveniles (under 18 years old) do not have the capacity to understand criminal law [2]. This law did not bestow any Due Process rights and other Procedural Guarantees because the state functioned as “parens patriae”. In this sense, the state is the guardian of the children and has the power to intervene in their education, orientation and treatment. When a child committed a crime, the parents have failed in their task of educating their children; therefore, the state has to intervene and function as a tutor searching for their “wellbeing”. Even though the imprisonment was the “treatment” for children (separate for adults), it was understood that the state did not punish the delinquent children, it was education. For this reason, it was not necessary confer any procedural right to the children; the state was protecting them instead of punishing. United Nations beholden to the states to recognize that imprisonment is punishment and it was necessary to provide procedural rights to juvenile delinquents. For this purpose, a new law was enacted in 1991: The “Juvenile Treatment Law for the Federal District”. It regulates state level crimes for the Federal District and federal crimes for the rest of the republic [8]. The objective of this law is established in its first statute: “…[It] Rules the function of the State in protecting juvenile rights as well as in the social adjustment of those whose conduct is typified within the federal laws and in those of the federal District law” [8]. This is an administrative court, since all the officials that constitute the juvenile council are administrative authorities (non-judiciary). The structure of the tribunal changed significantly from the previous. A president, a single counselor (in Mexico this is called Unitarian), a superior court (appeal body), an interdisciplinary committee (which issues the diagnosis), and a juvenile defense unit formed this tribunal. Unlike the former tribunals, a Unitarian counselor makes the resolutions during the process. In 2007, a new law for the Federal District, the “Law of Justice for Adolescents for the Federal District” was decreed, which included the new treatment for juveniles proposed under the Mexican Constitution and the Convention on the Rights of the Child [9]. The objective of this new law is to establish an integral system of justice for adolescents (“Sistema Integral de justicia para adolescentes” in Spanish) guaranteeing all their Constitutional rights including the right of Due Process, and institutionalization as a last resort. This Law creates judicial courts for adolescents, eliminating the administrative tribunals in existence before 2007. In 2005, Article 18 of the Constitution [6] was modified to establish an integral system of justice for adolescents between 12 and 18 years old, who had committed a crime punishable under the criminal law. Its objective was to guarantee juveniles all the due process rights established for adults, in addition to the special ones recognized for minors. The constitutional reform also provides a framework that includes special tribunals as well as alternative justice options for juveniles. With these reforms, institutionalization of minors was to be considered an extreme measure applicable only to felonies and to juveniles older than 14 years old [10]. In 2006, all states within the Mexican federation enacted the “New Law of justice for adolescents”. This system, at both the federal and state levels, formalizes a new global paradigm with regard to the triangular relationship between children, the State and the law. It accepts that children are also holder of the inherent human rights recognized for all individuals, instead of simply objects in need of protection. However, despite formally aligning Mexican juvenile justice law with the Convention on the Rights of the Child (CRC) [11], issues of actual substantive rights remained and new ones have appeared. For example, juveniles younger than 14 who have not committed a felony are released from Laws 2014, 3 583 institutions without any rehabilitation or treatment options, and alternative forms of justice were included without evaluating their possibilities of application or their conditions for success. In addition, the economic status of most juvenile detainees continues to be one of the most important determining factors in the administration of justice. Juveniles lack real access to an adequate defense because they cannot afford to pay lawyers. This disconnects between rights and reality undermines the new system, raising the question of whether recent modifications to bring laws in line with international norms are in fact advancing juvenile justice. By approaching the Mexican juvenile justice systems as a single, multilayered system combining international, federal and local laws and procedures, we can better describe some of the substantive inconsistencies that continue to prevail, even as new ones develop in terms of children’s rights. 2. International Influence Mexico ratified the United Nations Convention on the Rights of the Child in 1990 [11], thus making this treaty part of the supreme law. Article 18 of the Mexican Constitution [6] is the constitutional foundation for juvenile justice, wherein the Federal and State governments are required to create, regulate and administer a juvenile justice system within their respective legal systems. In 2005, the Mexican Constitution was modified, establishing an integral system of justice for juvenile delinquents (article 18) [6], including alternative forms of justice, and its operation by specialized institutions and authorities. Almost all Mexican states modified their Juvenile Justice Laws in 2006 to conform to the new constitutional provisions. However, despite bringing Mexican law in line with the CRC, several problems persist, and new ones have appeared. Therefore, the aim of this paper is to analyze whether and to what extent these new legal modifications constitute progress in the protection of children’s rights. 3. Procedural System The Mexican Constitution (article 18) [6] establishes the accusatory system for juvenile justice, implying the division and separation of the investigation and judgment functions during the juvenile trial. The judge cannot proceed to the investigation, prosecution or accusation of the offenses; he/she decides about the law and facts presented in the trial. Moreover, it is assumed there will be contradiction, debate, equal opportunities for the parties, and ample recognition of defense rights [12]. The accusatory procedural system will be applied for the first time in the juvenile justice system under the Law of Justice for Adolescents. The previous law (Law that Creates the Juvenile Tutelary Council) operated under the inquisitorial system; it was characterized by the concentration of the investigation and judgment functions within one institution [13]. The counselor was the person who executed those functions. However, within the accusatory system the investigation is executed by one legal body and the judgment is handed down by another. The new system decrees that the investigation is the purview of the specialized prosecutor (fiscal) and the judgment, that of the juvenile judge. This regulation claims to assure the right to impartiality in the trial and the respect of due process rights for minors. Another difference between the two laws is that in the inquisitorial judicial system the instruction phase is fundamental for the process; sentences are based on the trials produced during this stage. However, in the accusatory system there is only a single preparatory stage of the trial. Laws 2014, 3 584 The new law includes the phases of investigation, instruction, trial and application of measures. The specialized prosecutor (fiscal) conducts the investigation stage. The stages of instruction and judgment are the responsibility of the specialized judge, and the application of measures to a treatment institute. The instruction phase consists of previous diligence conducted to determine the nature and circumstances of the criminal act and the identity of the people who have participated in it. The law also establishes the resources of appeal, revision, revocation, and complaint in diverse instances; they could be claimed before a superior court. In the adversarial system, an impartial person makes the decision about the case; usually a judge or jury and two institutions operate to persuade the judge (prosecutors against defense) as to the culpability or innocence of the defendant [14]. Under new law, a special prosecutor officer conducts the investigation of the case. The prosecutor rather than the judge direct this stage, and the evidence obtained is taken into consideration by the judge in deciding the case. However, it is argued in the literature that this situation could maintain impartiality because one of the parties is in charge of the facts and the judge does not directly obtain the evidence [13]. Moreover, a real defense for most juveniles is difficult because they cannot afford a private lawyer. The state provides free defense for all adolescents; however, there are 5 defense attorneys for 500 juvenile delinquents in each state. Therefore, the principles of equal opportunities for the parties and ample recognition of defense rights are not reached. The state has all the resources to investigate and find proofs to condemn the adolescent, and most of the time; juveniles lack the resources to ensure a suitable defense. 4. Principles of Law that Establish the Integral System of Justice for Adolescents 4.1. Best Interest of the Child The Law that Establishes the Integral System of Justice for Adolescents states the “best interest of the child” is the most important principle. Mexican jurisprudence (decisions of the Supreme Court of justice) states that In considering the articles 4th of the Political Constitution of Mexico; 3rd of the Convention on the Rights of the child (ratified by Mexico and published in the Official Federation Newspaper on 25 January 1991); and 3rd, 4th, 6th and 7th of the Law for the Protection of the Rights of Children and Adolescents, the courts must primarily apply the best interest of the child in all the measures that concern the child. The Convention principle “best interest of the child” was construed by the Inter-American Court of Human Rights on 16 December 1998 when ratified the Inter-American Convention of Human Rights) as implying that children’s development and the total exercise of their rights, must be considered as the governing criteria for the elaboration of norms and the application of these in all the orders relative to the life of the child [15]. The Supreme Court in Mexico established that the principle of the “best interest of the child” is conceived as the means through which his/her total and integral development are achieved, and this includes providing to him/her the care and necessary attention to effect this [16]. Laws 2014, 3 585 4.1.1. How Should “Best Interest” Be Interpreted? Related to the Child’s Individual’s Needs? In the literature, there is no concise interpretation of the best interest standard. However, one traditional interpretation is the consideration that “parents know what is best for the child”. A more recent explanation is that the State knows what the best interest of the child is, and using the parens patriae power, can decide for the child [17]. “Best interest” has also been interpreted as responding to children’s wishes and in terms of their rights and developmental needs, taking into account their physical and psychological health. The position and autonomy of the child is recognized in interpreting the best interest standard [17]. The participation of the child in determining what could be her/his best interest and influencing decisions concerning her/him is the central point of the CRC Convention. Consequently, authorities cannot make decisions on what constitutes the best interests of an individual child without taking that child’s views into account [18]. Therefore, the best interest of the child is associated with the right of the child to be heard, in addition to due process rights, religious freedom, freedom of speech and respect of his/her own opinions. Rodriguez [19] indicates that the best interest of the child should be understood as the physical and emotional stability of the child, in a context of respect for her/his decisions; in conclusion, taking into account the fundamental development of his/her personality. The state of Veracruz, México states that the best interest of the child in concrete situations means [20]: 1. The opinion of the child (the right to be heard), 2. The equilibrium between the rights and obligations of the child, 3. The equilibrium between the requirements of the common good, the rights and guarantees of the child, 4. The equilibrium between the rights of persons and the rights of the child, 5. The specific condition of the child as a developing person. CRC states that children should be recognized as separate human beings from their parents, and that they can have their own interests, which may conflict with those of their parents [11]. The CRC article 12 establishes that “States Parties shall assure to the child who is capable of forming his or her own views the right to express those views freely in all matters affecting the child, the views of the child being given due weight in accordance with the age and maturity of the child” [11]. It also indicates that the child can express those views directly, or through a representative or appropriate body. Therefore, it is important to establish at what age children can form their own views and when they can express them directly. Under current Mexican law, children under 18 years old can express their views only through their representatives (Mexican Federal Civil Code, article 23) [21]. However, the goal of the Convention is direct expression by the child. Thus, the right of children to be heard, at least on matters of personal importance for them, originates from a view of the child as separate from their parents [22]. Child participation in court proceedings is therefore considered a manifestation of respect for children’s rights. The denial of the direct participation of the child in court proceedings could be considered as affecting the child’s personhood [22]. The right to be heard constitutes the direct participation of children in expressing their opinions in matters important to them. The Federal Law for the Protection of Children and Adolescents (2000) in turn establishes that children can express their opinion related to matters that affect them and other subjects connected Laws 2014, 3 586 to their family and community (article 41) [23]. However, the Federal Court has interpreted this right differently. In 2000, the Supreme Court determined that the Juvenile Law of Tamaulipas State violated the child’s right to be heard because it did not provide children with the opportunity to designate a representative to intervene in their defense. Children must be heard in a trial, in order to fulfill the guarantee of hearing, before depriving them of their liberty [24]. 4.1.2. What does the “Best Interest of the Child” Mean in Relation to His/Her Protection in the Process? Dagdug-Kalife [13], considers four basic protection rights to determine the best interest of the child: (a) the right to privacy; (b) precautionary treatment or measures; (c) alternative measures; and (d) protection. The right to privacy. The Convention establishes privacy in all stages of the proceedings. It legislates to protect the normal physical and psychological development of the child. Precautionary treatment or measures. Measures should be directed to child protection and take into consideration the presumption of innocence enshrined in the Convention. In this sense, the privation of freedom should be the last resort. Alternative measures. The process could finish in the first stages through care, guidance, supervision orders, mediation, conciliation, restoration or any alternative measure. Protection. It should be implemented to avoid stigmatization due to the crime committed. This best interest of the child principle appear after the Constitutional reform in Mexico. It is shown in Table 1. Table 1. Understanding of the best interest of the child in Mexican states juvenile justice laws. Explanation on the law for justice of adolescents Before the reform After the reform No mention 29 0 Maximize the rights of adolescents 0 4 Mention that it is a basic principle but, not explain it 0 9 Respect of all the children’s rights 0 4 Effective fulfillment of the children´s rights and guaranties 0 9 Optimal development 0 2 Increased quality of personhood 0 1 Total 29 29 The best interest of the child is directed to child protection and the satisfaction of their needs; however, state intervention in the case of juvenile delinquents is most directed to punish the criminal acts. The state does not seek the fulfillment of children rights and wellbeing during the process for juvenile delinquents. The process is directed to pursue the delinquent, similar to adults, and find the grade of guiltily of the adolescent. It is supposed that the state will find the optimal measure to achieve their healthy and optimal development. The most frequent option is incarceration, the use of alternative measures is scarce; state does not have the structure for applying them. Incarceration deprives children of opportunities for healthy socialization, family attachment, and education. Therefore, it does not help to reach the optimal development of the children, as it is established in the Mexican Constitution and Convention. Laws 2014, 3 587 4.2. Principe of Legality The Convention on the Rights of the Child declares “no child shall be accused by act or omissions not previously prohibited by the national or international law” [11]. The Mexican Constitution (article 18) recognizes this [6]. The previous laws (Law that Creates the Juvenile Tutelary Council) established that measures up to and including institutionalization could be applied to minors committing antisocial acts, but it did not define antisocial behavior. Article 14 of the Mexican Constitution establishes the principle of no crime without sanction and no sanction without law (nullum crimen sine poena, nullum poena sine lege certa) [6]. It states, “In a criminal trial it is prohibited to impose, by analogy or majority of reason, a sanction not established in the law which is exactly applicable to the crime”. The standard is the exact application of the law in view of the facts and it constitutes the fundamental principle of legality. The definition of this principle in the new system implies that measures can be applied only after a non-appealed judgment is obtained, dictated by a competent judge in a due process and under the form prescribed by the law. It also means that any adolescent can suffer restrictions of his/her liberty only because of a judge’s sanction [25]. The Supreme Court establishes the legality of the authorities’ restraint in its public power, which can only be exerted in conformity with the law and the faculties it grants [26]. This principle derives from article 14 of the Mexican Constitution, which states the restricted exigency of concrete contents, meaning that law should be neither vague or imprecise nor open or ample enough to allow arbitrariness [27]. In sum, the principle of legality constitutes the exact application of criminal law and the administration of previously established laws for criminal acts. The liberty of adolescents can be restricted only when a previously established law and tribunal have judged them and a non-appealed judgment has been obtained. Table 2 shows that before the reform antisocial behavior or indiscipline could be considered for arresting any children. After the reform of 2006 children could be arrested only for crimes established by the law. This is one of achievements of the new law. Table 2. Legality principle. Type Number of states Before reform After reform Children abandoned, when parents asked and crimes established in criminal law 1 0 Indiscipline and crimes established in the law 1 0 Antisocial behavior and crimes established in the law 24 0 Crimes established in the law 0 29 No data 3 0 Total 29 29 4.3. Diversion The CRC (article 40) promotes the possibility of extrajudicial measures, while respecting children’s rights [11]. The article 18 of Mexican Constitution establishes that, when possible, alternative forms of justice should be utilized [6]. Thus, the new system foresees pre-judicial or extra-judicial instances of conflict resolution and favors a non-judicial process, using the principles of minimal intervention and Laws 2014, 3 588 the best interest of the child. Reducing the use of the judicial system implies the existence of an alternative solution for criminal processes [28]. In some states of the Mexican Republic, mediation and conciliation are considered alternative forms of justice. For example, in Sonora State, article 9, fraction XVI [29]. Nuevo León State favors restorative justice, which is defined as the voluntary juridical act conducted between the victim and the accused children that results in the solution of the conflict through any suitable mechanism (article 62) [30]. In Sonora State, mediation could occur during the procedure or before pronouncing the resolution (article 155). Conciliation and mediation are utilized in repairing the damage that results from crime. These alternative forms are allowed for crimes that are prosecuted at the request of the offended party and they allow the extinction of the criminal action when legal disinterestedness of the victim in the continuation of the cause exists (article 156) [29]. All states of the Mexican Republic consider the judicial process as the last resort in the treatment of juvenile offenders, and in many states, the law promotes the use of alternative processes. However, few states allow these processes to be carried out it in a center for alternative justice. In addition, alternative systems exist for misdemeanors but in some of them, it is difficult to have recourse to them because of a number of prerequisites for their use [25]. Two Mexican states (Querétaro [31] and Chiapas [32]) contemplate extra-judicial process; however, their legal systems indicate that a judge will prescribe psychological assistance for the processed adolescent, who must repair the harm inflicted on the victim. Most of the state’s laws authorize judges and public prosecutors to settle agreements through mediation and conciliation, yet, some states request the intervention of specialized public or private centers; for example, Durango [33] State redirects the process to an alternative center of justice. Table 3 shows the number of states that considered diversion for adolescents. Table 3. States that consider diversion for adolescents. Type Number of states Before reform After reform Conciliation 0 5 Mediation and conciliation 0 10 Mediation, conciliation and restorative justice 0 2 Conciliation and suspended process to proof 0 6 Mediation, conciliation and suspended process 0 3 Restorative justice and suspended process 0 1 Restoration, mediation, conciliation, and suspended process 0 2 Total 0 29 A real extra-judicial process carried out in the community, school contexts, or in a combination of these, is not recognized by law. An alternative process conducted outside of the court is not possible under the Mexican system, only one state considers an alternative center of justice. Considering former arguments alternative process for juveniles is not possible and it is essential to ensure a healthy social and psychological development of adolescents. Laws 2014, 3 589 4.4. Due Process Rights and Other Procedural Guarantees The Mexican Constitution (article 18) and juvenile justice laws recognize that the procedural guarantees of adults have to be granted to juveniles; moreover, these legal frameworks enshrine the special guarantees granted for persons under 18 years old (children and adolescents) and their due process rights [6]. The due process rights constitute the principles, rights and guarantees that protect persons against arbitrary acts by authority, conferring on them a strong status in the presence of punitive action by the state. These protections include the rights to be judged in judicial tribunals, to be heard, of contradiction and defense, the presumption of innocence, the right to an oral trial, the establishment of the means of incrimination, and the accusatory system. For children, due process rights conceive them as subjects of rights and procedural guarantees granted to all persons, but those rights also provide special guarantees because of their condition [34]. The Interamerican Court of Human Rights stated that in the application of these rights the special condition of the child should be taken into consideration [35]. Table 4 indicates the number of states that contemplate the presumption of innocence before and after the reform. Table 4. Presumption of innocence principle. Type Number of states Before reform After reform No guarantee for adolescents 25 0 Guarantee for adolescents 4 29 Total 29 29 In the case of children, due process rights should be respected in all the stages of the process, even during the application of the treatment. The due process rights granted by this law are: the right to be informed about the due process rights; to not be private of freedom just for cases established by the law; to be respected; to presumption of innocence; to not be forced to testify; to guarantee that the burden of proof should be charged to their prosecutors; to be informed about procedural acts; to short preventive institutionalization; to the presence of their parents or tutors in all stages of the diligence; to the right to privacy; to the right to an appropriate defense (which includes the right to counsel and the right to a state-appointed attorney when no other counsel has been designated); to the right to an interpreter in case of being indigenous or not Spanish-speaking; to have access to all information available for their defense; to an expeditious, complete and impartial trial; to present any evidence regulated by Criminal Law; to confront and cross-examine witnesses; to assure notification of their parents or guardians regarding the charges; to appeal the resolutions; to be notified about the charges, and the right to privacy and confidentiality. Children have the right to respect of their privacy and that of their families, thus they have the right to non-disclosure of any information about their identity (name, address, relationships, picture, etc.) at any stage of the process. All the authorities intervening in the process have the obligation to maintain confidentiality regarding all information that could lead to the identification of the child. Some Mexican states mandate this obligation as applied to their police forces and prosecutors. All publicity related to children’s cases is prohibited. The right to intervention means that the adolescent should have enough time to prepare his/her defense and participate in all the hearings of the process, to have access to all the documents, have the Laws 2014, 3 590 right to formulate questions to witnesses, to present allegations and other important arguments for the defense, and to propose and contradict proofs. The right to be informed implies that children should be informed concerning all their rights and all aspects of the process. Children should receive information in a simple and clear form, according to their capacity to comprehend. This information could vary depending on their age, contents of the law, the meaning of the process diligences, the object, purpose, motive and duration of the measures, and so on. This has two objectives for children: to ensure that they understand the value of the prescribed judicial actions and grasp the educational function of those actions. Non-discrimination is another essential right for adolescents. However, the law does not define it; it merely describes the causes of discrimination. The law indicates the right of equality, and non-discrimination for reasons of gender, religion, race, ethnic origin, language, nationality, cultural practices or beliefs, special capacities, social mal-adaptation, nature and seriousness of behavior, political preference, parents’ situation, and economic and social condition. The non-discrimination right is also considered in the application of measures. The absolute impartiality of their execution, under the supervision of a judge, is established. The law also contemplates special protection for native, female and handicapped adolescents. In spite of this, the state grants all procedural rights to adolescents, for example precautionary prison is considered in all states of Mexico, it is established for exceptional cases and for minimal time. However, all adolescents that break the law are arrested immediately and remain in jail until the sentence. 4.5. Application of Measures The Mexican Constitution [6] denominates “measures” by the state in response to those responses contravening Criminal Law. These measures constitute real penalties or sanctions because they imply the adolescent’s responsibility for their criminal offences. The Senate, in passing the law, explained the term “measures” was used to differentiate them from penalties applied in the adult system because the latter involves individuals possessing mens rea. Measures aim to eliminate the retributive goal of sanctions; the Mexican Constitution [6] establishes that the purpose of measures is “the familiar and social rehabilitation of the adolescent to reach a complete development of her/his person and capacities”. Therefore, according to the Constitution, the measures or treatment have an educational function. The administration of measures should be flexible and the judge applies discretion in their administration in order to respect the minors’ due process rights. The objective is to find the most appropriate measure for the adolescent’s rehabilitation. The juvenal system of justice establishes very diverse measures for adolescents who violate Criminal Law, ranging from a warning and reprimand to systems of semi-freedom or institutionalization. Mainly, two kinds of measures are applicable to adolescents: one is institutionalization; another is external measures consisting of orientation, protection, education and treatment. Institutionalization is considered an extreme measure applicable only to felonies and to juveniles older than 14 [6] (article 18). Some Mexican states include other forms of deprivation of freedom, for example domiciliary arrest (23 states, constituting the majority of states), free-time arrest (11 states), semi-open system (16 states), and weekend arrest (12 states) [25]. Deprivation of freedom should be the last resort, consisting of the shortest incarceration time possible. There is no regulation to define this disposition and each state determines what “the shortest time” is. In some states, it depends Laws 2014, 3 591 on the age and the severity of the crime. In addition, some states consider different gradations of deprivation of freedom, and the judge has to justify the use of the extreme measure of institutionalization. However, in reality the law increased the maximum years of penalties and incarceration. The next table (Table 5) shows a comparison of the penalties before and after of constitutional reform. Table 5. Penalties that establish the laws for juvenile delinquents in the different states of Mexico before the reform of 2006 and after the reform. Maximum Years of penalties Number of States Before of reform After the reform 5 20 3 6 1 0 7 2 12 8 0 3 10 0 5 12 0 1 15 0 2 18 0 1 20 0 1 22 1 0 No exceed the penalty for adults 0 1 Undefined 1 0 No data 4 0 Total 29 29 All states establish rights for children who are subject to institutionalization and indicate that the intervention must be tailored to the individual child’s needs. In addition, it is agreed that children should be heard in the elaboration of this individualized program. Indeed, their agreement to the program is important for the accomplishment of the measure and the goal of the intervention system. The purpose of rehabilitation of the new law is converted into an increased time of incarceration. 4.6. Proportionality of Measures The CRC [11] establishes in article 40 that a correlation should exist between punitive measures, the circumstances of the crime and the severity of the infraction. Punitive measures should be prescribed according to the goal of the integral system, which is the education of the adolescent. Therefore judges should impose the most appropriate sanction to strengthen the child’s rights, freedom and developmental, as well as the social integration of adolescents [25]. For example, the law of Justice for Adolescents in Sonora [29] indicates that, in determining a measure, the Judge will have to consider: first the best interests of the child, and second, various global characteristics of the case, such as life circumstances and the severity of the criminal conduct, the adolescent’s age, the conditions of his/her development, the adolescent’s attitude during the process, his/her efforts carried out to repair the harm, and the possibility that the adolescent will fulfil the prescribed punitive measures (article 83). With these dispositions, the law tries to adhere to the principle of proportionality in the application of punitive measures. Moreover, the law states that these measures should always favor the interests of Laws 2014, 3 592 the adolescent; for this reason, it is important that the judge consider the juvenile’s needs and circumstances, because they can affect his or her behavior. Adverse social and familial conditions experienced by the adolescent should mitigate the sanction, rather than aggravate it. Increasing time of incarceration does not favor the social and familiar rehabilitation and development of the children; therefore, the application of the law does not reach the best interest of the child. 4.7. Specialization The CRC [11], the Mexican Constitution [6] (article 18) as well as the Justice for Adolescents [29] state that any process will be conducted in specialized institutions, by specialized authorities and courts. The specialization is also extended to the administration of punitive measures; the new law requires specialized personnel for the elaboration of programs for adolescents subject to “institutionalization and application of other punitive measures” [25]. Specialized courts have been created to administer justice for adolescents, in the context of the judicial power of the state. With this establishment of specialized courts, the juvenile courts in Mexico [29] moved from an administrative to a judicial context (article 22). Provisional custody, the execution of external measures and the institutionalization of adolescents will be administered by the Institute of Treatment and Application of Measures for Adolescents, under the authority of the Executive Secretary of Public Security of the State [29] (article 23). This law also created the Specialized Unit of Prosecution of Justice for Adolescents, part of the General Prosecution Office of the State. The position of specialized prosecutor in the administration of justice for adolescents was also created. This unit will prosecute and investigate the crimes of adolescents (article 16) [29]. The law also mandated the establishment of the Specialized Unit for the Defense of Adolescents, under the authority of the General Direction of the Official Counselling (Government institution). This specialized unit will provide adolescents with assistance, legal representation, advice and defense of their rights during trial (article 16) [29]. The law establishes that the staff of these units should be carefully selected, demonstrating previous experience in the treatment of children, and competence in the management of children’s issues. Chihuahua State (article 118) [36] established that these personnel should exhibit “aptitudes to exercise the [expected] function, a gender perspective, knowledge of human rights, and specialization in adolescents in private practice”. Other states establish that staff should demonstrate knowledge of children’s rights and juvenile delinquency, as well as possess appropriate legal knowledge. Moreover, systematic and continuous training on the psychological, physical, and social development and needs of children is mandated. Furthermore, specialized background and training in children’s issues is a condition for hiring, granting of permanency and promotion of all personnel. Table 6 indicates the number of specialized judges before and after the reform. Table 6. Specialization of the judges. Type Number of states Before reform After reform No specialization 29 0 Specialization 0 29 Laws 2014, 3 593 The personnel of the system are: 1. Prosecutors 2. Police officers 3. Judges and magistrates 4. Public attorneys 5. Technical team 6. Institution for the execution of the measures 7. Directors of institutions of incarceration centers 8. Auxiliary team After the reform all the Juvenile system was modified, prosecutors, judges, and unit of defense are specialized. They receive an orientation about children rights, legal process and juvenile delinquency. However, there is no specialized police; adolescents are arrested for police officers that attend general population. 5. Concluding Remarks The new law radically changes the concept of the child, who is now considered a subject with rights and obligations instead of simply an object to be protected. The best interest of the child is the fundamental principle of the law, and full protection of children its main goal. However, these changes, designed for juveniles who contravene criminal law, have not modified their legal and social status. Application of the new principles has not improved their situation, in part because of ambiguities in definitions. The concept of integral protection, for example, is diffuse; there is no clear definition in the law. This system tries to responds to juvenile delinquency problems in a social scenario where there is a demand for solutions; through this system, the government addresses the issue of adolescents who contravene criminal law [28], although apparently, only in a conceptual or theoretical way. In contrast, alternative forms of justice could encourage the Mexican government to focus on the needs of children. This would also promote a more egalitarian system. The new system is directed to this end in theory, but the first step to an improved juvenile legal system would be the recognition that more than half of Mexican children live in poverty. If the State ignores this situation, it does not meet its responsibilities. The new system of protection involves providing education, promoting and guaranteeing health, and offering opportunities for complete human development. Although the proposal of the new juvenile legal system is the fulfilment of the needs of the adolescent, in practice, the system is more directed to social control. It tries to eliminate the undesirable behavior of adolescents through sanctions and by encouraging the juvenile to recognize his/her responsibility, while at the same time deterring other adolescents from committing crimes. Most Mexican States increased their penalties for adolescents. However, there is no real social service proportionating to adolescents the opportunity to receive social, familial, educational, and health support to develop a healthy lifestyle. Although institutionalization is intended for felonies, each state differs in its definition of a felony. Frequently, it is up to judges to decide what constitutes a felony for juveniles. In addition, adolescents could be incarcerated for any offense, increasing the probability for institutionalization. The instruction phase thus continues to be the most important part of the trial. Therefore, could be considered the new law has not changed this situation. Laws 2014, 3 594 Under new system a special prosecutor is designated to investigate juvenile cases. In practice, then, the prosecutor, not the judge, directs the investigation of the facts and this evidence is taken into consideration by the judge in deciding the case [13]. Such a situation threatens the impartiality of the proceeding because one of the parties directly involved is in charge of handling the facts. Moreover, the judge does not directly obtain the evidence. In conclusion, although the Mexican laws are responding to international requirements, the protection of children has not been achieved. In contrast, a complex, sometimes contradictory, system of pluralistic rules has developed, making the goal of children’s protection unreachable in the present context. Author Contributions The first author wrote the article and the second elaborated the tables. Conflicts of Interest The authors declare no conflict of interest. References and Notes 1. Robert C. Trojanowicz, and Merry Morash. Juvenile Delinquency: Concepts and Control. New Jersey: Prentice Hall, 1987, p. 517. 2. Luis Rodríguez-Manzanera. Criminalidad de Menores [Criminality of Minors]. Mexico City: Editorial Porrua, 1997, pp. 367–85. 3. D.O. (Official Journal) 21 de junio de 1928, Ley sobre la Prevención social de la Delincuencia Infantil en el Distrito Federal (Law Regarding Social Prevention and Juvenile Delinquency for the Federal District and Territories, 1928). 4. D.O. (Official Journal) 26 de Junio de 1941, Ley Orgánica y Normas de Procedimiento de los Tribunales de Menores y sus Instituciones Auxiliares en el Distrito y Territorio Federales (Fundamental Law and Procedure Rules of Children Courts and Its Auxiliary Institutions in District and Federal Territory). 5. Victoria Adato de Ibarra. “Derecho Procesal de Menores y la Constitución in Derecho de la Niñez.” In Memorias del Coloquio de Derechos de la Niñez del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas. Mexico City: Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México, 1990, pp. 91–108. (In Spanish) 6. Congreso de la Unión. Poder legislativo de los Estados Unidos Mexicanos. “Constitución Política de los Estados Unidos Mexicanos (Political Constitution of the United Mexican States).” Available online: http://www.diputados.gob.mx/LeyesBiblio/pdf/1_07jul14.pdf (accessed on 20 August 2014). 7. D.O. (Official Journal) 2 de agosto de 1974, Ley que Crea el Consejo Tutelar para Menores Infractores en el Distrito Federal. 8. D.O. (Official Journal) 27 de diciembre del 1991, Ley para el Tratamiento de Menores Infractores para el Distrito Federal en Materia Común y para toda la República en materia federal. 9. Asamblea Legislativa del Distrito Federal. VI Legislatura. “Ley de Justicia para Adolescentes para el Distrito Federal (Law of Justice for Adolescents of Federal District). Publicada en la Gaceta Oficial del D. F. el 17 de Noviembre de 2007.” Available online: Laws 2014, 3 595 http://www.aldf.gob.mx/archivo-102c072ba3aadbf6f952a4d2f77d5c1c.pdf (accessed on 20 August 2014). 10. D.O. (Official Journal) Diario Oficial de la Federación, 12 de diciembre de 2005. 11. Convention on the Rights of the Child (2009). Ratified by Mexico in 10 August 1990. (Convención Sobre los Derechos del Niño ratificado 10 de agosto de 1990). 12. Gomes Da Costa, and Antonio Carlos. “Futuro de las políticas Públicas para la Infancia en América Latina.” Available online: http://www.iin.oea.org/Futuro_para_las_politicas_ publicas.pdf (accessed on 13 August 2014). 13. Dagdug-Kalife, Alfredo. “Aspectos procesales de los asuntos de menores infractores.” In Derecho Penal. Memoria del Congreso Internacional de Culturas y Sistemas Jurídicos Comparados. Edited by S. García Ramírez. México City: Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas UNAM, 2005, pp. 180–206. Available online: http://www.bibliojuridica.org/libros/4/1727/11.pdf (accessed on 25 March 2009). (In Spanish) 14. Bakken, Tim. “Truth and innocence procedures to free innocent persons: Beyond the adversarial system.” University of Michigan Journal of Law Reform 41 (2008): 547–95. 15. Semanario Judicial de la Federación (hereinafter S.J.F.). Primera Sala (First Chamber), Novena Época. Tesis: 1a. CXLI/2007; Pagina 265. The best interest of the child. 16. Semanario Judicial de la Federación (hereinafter S.J.F.). Primera Sala (First Chamber), Novena Época. Tesis: II.3o.C.13 K; 2005, Pagina 1798. Custody and the best interest of the child. 17. Henderson, Tammy L. “Grandparent Visitation Rights: Justices’ Interpretation of the Best Interests of the Child Standard.” Journal of Family Issues 26 (2005): 638–64. 18. Lidén, Hilde, and Hilde Rusten. “Asylum, participation and the best interest of the child: New lessons from Norway.” Children & Society 21 (2007): 273–83. 19. Rodriguez, Sonia. La protección de los menores en el Derecho Internacional Privado Mexicano. México City: Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas UNAM, 2006. Available online: http://www.bibliojuridica.org/libros/libro.htm?l=2197 (accessed on 25 March 2009). (In Spanish) 20. Congreso del Estado de Veracruz. Poder Legislativo del Estado de Veracruz. “Ley de Responsabilidad Juvenil para el Estado de Veracruz Ignacio de la llave (art. 9).” Available online: http://www.legisver.gob.mx/leyes/LeyesPDF/RESPONSABILIDADJUVENIL09-03-07.pdf (accessed on 25 March 2009). 21. Congreso de la Unión. Poder legislativo de los Estados Unidos Mexicanos. “Código Civil Federal (Federal Civil Code).” Available online: http://www.diputados.gob.mx/LeyesBiblio/pdf/ 2_241213.pdf (accessed on 20 August 2014). 22. Grover, Sonja. “The right of the child to be heard in education litigation: An analysis of the ‘intelligent design’ Pennsylvania case on the separation of Church and State in the public schools.” Education and the Law 18 (2006): 149–60. 23. Congreso de la Unión. Poder legislativo de los Estados Unidos Mexicanos. “Ley Para La Protección De Los Derechos De Niñas, Niños Y Adolescentes (Federal Law for the Protection of Children and Adolescents).” Available online: http://www.diputados.gob.mx/LeyesBiblio/pdf/ 185.pdf (accessed on 20 August 2014). 24. D.O. (Official Journal) Semanario Judicial de la Federación (hereinafter S.J.F.). Primera sala (Second Chamber), Novena Época. Amparo directo en Revisión 397; 2000, Página 181. Juvenile Laws 2014, 3 596 delinquents: Law for prevention of Antisocial Behavior, Assistance to Victims, Tutelary Measures and Social Readjustment for Children in the State of Tamaulipas, violates hearing guarantee because it does not anticipate the intervention, in the process, of the person that exerts the custody or the advocate of their confidence (Law published in the official gazette, 27 December 1986). 25. Vasconcelos-Mendez, Rubén. La justicia para Adolescentes en México: Análisis de las leyes Estatales. México City: Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas de la UNAM, 2009. Available online: http://www.bibliojuridica.org/libros/6/2640/pl2640.htm (accessed on 24 April 2009). (In Spanish) 26. Semanario Judicial de la Federación (hereinafter S.J.F.). Tribunal Colegiado de circuito en materia Administrativa, primer cuito (Fist Circuit), Novena Época. Tesis aislada I.7o.A.511 A /2007. Página 1673. Competence by territory of the administrative authorities. The fact that an individual voluntarily attends an authority’s request does not imply a tacit submission, attending the principle of legality anticipated in article 16 of the federal constitution. 27. Semanario Judicial de la Federación (hereinafter S.J.F.). Segundo tribunal Colegiado en materia Penal del Segundo Circuito (Segundo Circuit), Novena Época. Amparo directo 137/2005, Página 1879. Principle of legality standard constitutes the fundamental base and rule, with the principle of taxability and hermeneutic plenitude derived from the first, which is the base of a criminal system in a democratic state. 28. Belloff, Mary. “Los nuevos Sistemas de Justicia Juvenil en América Latina (1989–2006).” In Justicia y Derechos del Niño. Edited by Mary Beloff, Miguel Cillero, Emilio García Méndez, María Loreto Quijada, Gimol Pinto, Alejandro Gómez and Susana Falca. Santiago de Chile: UNICEF, 2006, vol. 8, pp. 9–50. 29. Congreso del Estado de Sonora. Poder Legislativo del Estado de Sonora México. “Ley que Establece el Sistema Integral de Justicia para Adolescentes del Estado de Sonora (The Law that Establishes the Integral System of Justice for minors in Sonora).” Available online: http://www.congresoson.gob.mx/Leyes_Archivos/doc_107.pdf (accessed on 20 August 2014). 30. Congreso del Estado de Nuevo León. Poder Legislativo del Estado de Nuevo León. “Ley del Sistema Especial de Justicia para Adolescentes Del Estado de Nuevo León.” Available online: http://www.hcnl.gob.mx/trabajo_legislativo/leyes/pdf/LEY%20DEL%20 SISTEMA%20ESPECIAL%20DE%20JUSTICIA%20PARA%20ADOLESCENTES%20DEL%2 0ESTADO%20DE%20NUEVO%20LEON.pdf (accessed on 12 August 2014). 31. Congreso del Estado de Querétaro. Poder Legislativo del Estado de Querétaro. “Ley de justicia para menores del estado de Querétaro.” Available online: http://info4.juridicas.unam.mx/adprojus/ leg/23/962/ (accessed on 12 January 2009). 32. Congreso del Estado de Chiapas. Poder Legislativo del Estado de Chiapas. “Ley para la protección y tratamiento de menores infractores para el Estado de Chiapas.” Available online: http://info4.juridicas.unam.mx/adprojus/leg/8/275/default.htm?s= (accessed on 20 January 2009). 33. Congreso del Estado de Durango. Poder Legislativo del Estado de Durango. “Código de Justicia para Menores del Estado de Durango.” Available online: http://congresodurango.gob.mx/ Leyes/CODIGO_DE_JUSTICIA_PARA_MENORES_INFRACTORES_EN_EL_ESTADO_DE_ DURANGO.pdf (accessed on 18 August 2014). Laws 2014, 3 597 34. Armijo Sáncho, Gilbert. Manual de Derecho Procesal Penal Juvenil. San José: ILANUD, 1998, p. 230. (In Spanish) 35. Inter-American Court for Human Rights. “Consultiva opinion OC-17/2002.” Available online: http://www.corteidh.or.cr/docs/opiniones/seriea_17_esp.pdf (accessed on 18 January 2009). 36. Congreso del Estado de Chihuahua. Poder Legislativo del Estado de Chihuahua. “Ley de Justicia Especial para Adolescentes infractores del Estado de Chihuahua.” Available online: http://www.congresochihuahua.gob.mx/biblioteca/leyes/archivosLeyes/87.pdf (accessed on 10 August 2014). © 2014 by the authors; licensee MDPI, Basel, Switzerland. This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0/). work_e6xz2kberfcgdaakki4adhms4u ---- wp-p1m-38.ebi.ac.uk Params is empty 404 sys_1000 exception wp-p1m-38.ebi.ac.uk no 221729145 Params is empty 221729145 exception Params is empty 2021/04/06-03:20:25 if (typeof jQuery === "undefined") document.write('[script type="text/javascript" src="/corehtml/pmc/jig/1.14.8/js/jig.min.js"][/script]'.replace(/\[/g,String.fromCharCode(60)).replace(/\]/g,String.fromCharCode(62))); // // // window.name="mainwindow"; .pmc-wm {background:transparent repeat-y top left;background-image:url(/corehtml/pmc/pmcgifs/wm-nobrand.png);background-size: auto, contain} .print-view{display:block} Page not available Reason: The web page address (URL) that you used may be incorrect. Message ID: 221729145 (wp-p1m-38.ebi.ac.uk) Time: 2021/04/06 03:20:25 If you need further help, please send an email to PMC. Include the information from the box above in your message. Otherwise, click on one of the following links to continue using PMC: Search the complete PMC archive. Browse the contents of a specific journal in PMC. Find a specific article by its citation (journal, date, volume, first page, author or article title). http://europepmc.org/abstract/MED/ work_e77xab7isnep3iiomaqvox7kvi ---- 250 Book reviews In recent years there has been an expanding literature devoted to the case stories of those who are ill, but this collection of articles is unusual in that it starts with this approach in part one, and then considers the ethical, social, cultural and political responses to them, attempting to provide a link with policy issues, in part two. This is an ambitious and important develop- ment which deserves far more atten- tion than it has received so far. The individual contributions to the volume are generally of a high stan- dard, and rather than attempt the briefest sketch of each of them, I will highlight certain issues which I found of particular interest. In the first chapter of part one Kay Toombs's description of her personal experi- ences - "Sufficient unto the day: a life with multiple sclerosis" - was both insightful and compelling. Two telling quotations speak for themselves. First that "...there is nothing intrinsically good about chronic, progressive multiple sclerosis. Nothing. This is not, however, to deny that my life has been profoundly affected in ways that are enriching" (page 20). Second: "Perhaps the greatest challenge of all for the multiple sclerosis patient is to learn to live with ongoing and perma- nent uncertainty" (page 20). In another chapter in part one, "Whose story is it anyway?", Sue Estroff analyses the ethical issues raised in doing narrative research on chronic illness. Estroff's own work has been with the long-term mentally ill and her sensitive and honest account exposes the impossibility of deriving ethical research practices from theo- retical considerations alone. In par- ticular she demonstrates the problem of applying ethical codes primarily developed for quantitative research on those with acute physical illness, to qualitative and especially narrative research with those with chronic mental illness. The central issue here is that narrative research requires that the researcher empathise and collabo- rate with the subjects of the study, whilst also being sufficiently distant from them to maintain a degree of objectivity. One ambiguity that arises from this is that in attempting to adopt a neutral stance the researcher may be seen by the research subject as the most caring person he or she has contact with. Estroff concludes that "the lines between friend and investi- gator blur over time, producing almost as many difficulties as positive contributions to the quality of the research" (page 91). In the second part of the book, which focuses on policy, John Douard's chapter "Disability and the persistence of the normal", is con- cerned with the distinction that arose in the nineteenth century between the normal and the abnormal, both medically and socially and the way it can lead to two responses to disability which tend to sustain conformity and discipline within society rather than solving problems of how to live together. These are, first, giving special rights to distinct minority groups, so institutionalising labelling; and, second, requiring people to behave in such a way as to "qualify" as normal, so that they are held respon- sible for their own status. These observations are important and demonstrate the relevance of social and historical analysis to ethical issues, a theme which Arthur Kleinman takes up in his chapter on "The social course of chronic illness": "I maintain that there is a role for anthropology, social history, and other social sciences in shifting the object of inquiry to include the social processes of everyday local worlds which shape suffering in ways quite distinct from the usual individual psychological orientation of clinical and ethical approaches taken to this most human of conditions [that of suffering]" (page 185). The difficu!ty though is how to put this process into operation and make it relevant to social policy; the struc- ture of the book is itself an indication of where the problem lies. The first part concentrates on the individual experience of suffering, and the second on how to harness that experi- ence in fostering better approaches to policy-making. However, the two parts are largely unrelated to each other. Only Estroff connects the direct accounts ofher own narrative research with ambiguities in its nature and so points to ethical dilemmas relating to research policy; and there is no attempt to form a bridge between the other chapters in the two parts of the book. This then is not just a collection of interesting articles, because it raises the question of how to bring together illness narrative research with more traditional historical, sociological and anthropological approaches in such a way as to enrich the overall analysis and more fruitfully inform social policy. Although the book is limited in how far it has taken this project forward, the distinction of many of the contributions is in having shown the importance of this area for the future. DAVID GREAVES Centre for Philosophy and Health Care, University of Wales, Swansea Justice and Health Care: Comparative Perspectives Edited by Andrew Grubb and Maxwell J Mehlman, John Wiley, Chichester, 1995, 350 pages, £35.00. Limited resources and rationing are "buzz words" today in health care across the globe. The development of modem medical technology with its ability to prolong life has at the same time raised the dilemma of just who should get the treatment? justice and Health Care: Comparative Perspectives, a collection of essays which, as the title suggests, discusses particular problems relating to health care allocation in the light of experiences drawn from a number of jurisdictions, is thus a timely publication. A number of essays concentrate on broad questions of policy in resource allocation. For instance, Alan Maynard, an economist, examines rationing - currently one of the most hotly debated issues within the National Health Service (NHS). Maynard argues for the establishment of criteria for resource alloca- tion within the NHS, drawing upon experiences in Oregon and elsewhere. While overt resource allocation decisions may prove a difficult and uncomfortable task, some may see this as preferable to the somewhat covert allocation process undertaken in the past. Physicians on both sides of the Atlantic have taken into account a patient's lifestyle in deciding whether to undertake treatment. Robert Schwartz questions this in his essay "Life style, health status and distribu- tive justice". For example, decisions regarding lifestyle may not be truly voluntary - the fact that an individual becomes an alcoholic may relate to a whole series of factors beyond whether or not an individual chooses to have a drink. In addition, he doubts whether restriction of resources on lifestyle criteria is justifi- able on the basis of punishment or of deterrence. Many of the essays in this collec- tion address the role of the law in o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://jm e .b m j.co m / J M e d E th ics: first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /jm e .2 2 .4 .2 5 0 o n 1 A u g u st 1 9 9 6 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://jme.bmj.com/ Book reviews 251 facilitating access to health care. The difficulties with legal recognition of rights to health care are explored by Dieter Giesen. Some of the themes considered by Professor Giesen, notably the duty to rescue, are also taken up in Barry Furrow's essay examining provision of care to persons falling outside the health insurance scheme in the USA. Lawrence Gostin in his essay "The Americans with Disabilities Act and the corpus of anti-discrimination law: a force for change in the future of public health legislation", discusses the extent to which public health powers in the USA conflict with the rights of persons with communicable diseases and the role which can be played by anti-discrimination legisla- tion in the form of the Americans with Disabilities Act. Deficiencies in health provision and sensitivity to the particular needs of ethnic groups in England are considered by David Pearl. This essay also illustrates the existing difficulties in attempting to use English law as a means of obtaining access to health care resources. The remaining essays provide: an examination of dimensions of justice in the context of the operation of the Canadian Health system, by Carolyn Tuhoy; the use of financial incentives in a market in organs, by James Blumstein, and problems of access to health care experienced by those from the USA African- American community, by Vernellia E Randall. All the essays in the collection explore the central theme in the con- text of a well-developed Western health care system. It perhaps should be borne in mind that a comparative analysis of matters regarding justice and health care in relation to, for example, the Third World, would of course, bring into focus somewhat dif- ferent issues. While some essays draw cross-jurisdictional comparisons the primary focus of this collection is American, with five out of nine of the essays concentrating upon American health care. The collection is thus per- haps not truly "comparative". Never- theless, overall J7ustice and Health Care: Comparative Perspectives provides a number of lively, provocative and scholarly contributions to what is becoming an increasingly vociferous debate. J V McHALE Lecturer in Law, Faculty of Law, University of Manchester Torture: Human Rights, Medical Ethics and the Case of Israel Edited by Neve Gordon and Ruchama Marton, London, Zed Books, 1995, 206 pages, £42.50 hc, £16.95 sc. The book derives from a conference on the International Struggle against Torture and the Case of Israel, held in Tel-Aviv in 1993, organised by the Association of Israeli-Palestinian Physicians for Human Rights and the Public Committee against Torture in Israel. It is not merely a proceedings, but a compilation by seventeen of the participants with diverse interests and skills, though it does include reports of workshops held at the end of each section of the conference. Considering the composition of the population of Israel and the past personal experiences of many of its citizens, it might be thought that the very idea of torture would be anathema. However, it is a tragic fact that the whole history of Israeli- Palestinian relationships has been tainted by allegations ofinhuman treat- ment on both sides, but particularly by Israeli soldiers and interrogators. The book is divided into four parts. The first, dealing with the public realm takes the political status first, des- cribing how harsh treatment amount- ing to torture has not been condemned but made legitimate by the Landau Report. In 1987 a commission of inquiry headed by ChiefJustice Moshe Landau, was set up to investigate com- plaints of ill-treatment of Palestinian detainees. The commission, instead of outlawing torture, authorised the General Security Service (GSS) to use "a moderate measure of physical force" in the interrogation of "secur- ity" detainees. The recommendations became law. Though the exact methods permitted have never been published, the interpretation of "mod- erate physical force" has led to the use of such techniques as beating, hood- ing, sleep deprivation, confining in a cupboard-sized cell, electric shocks and vigorous shaking. Next, the social response to the situation is described. There are three lines of argument commonly used: i: To deny that tor- ture takes place except as an occa- sional aberration; ii: Avoiding the use of pejorative words and substituting phrases such as "moderate physical pressure" or what the French in Algiers called "special procedures"; and iii: Acknowledging its use but justifying it by claiming that harsh measures are necessary to bring the emergency to a more speedy con- clusion. Even "liberal" sections of the community are guilty of these decep- tions, colluding with the majority in turning a blind eye. The second section deals with the involvement of health professionals in torture. It is alleged that a doctor is in the background behind every torturer/ interrogator. He performs a pre- torture examination, monitors the tor- ture process, examines and takes care of the prisoner following the infliction of torture and writes a medical opin- ion or a pathology report. A form of "Fitness for torture" used by the Department of Interrogation asks the doctor to certify whether there are any medical reasons for limitations to a stay in an isolated cell, chaining, hooding or prolonged standing. When the Israeli-Palestinian Physicians for Human Rights protested to the Israeli Medical Association (IMA) about this form, their chairperson, Dr Miriam Tzangen, wrote urgently to the Prime Minister. He replied that it was simply experimental and its use would be dis- continued. Apart from this example, the IMA has remained silent over the mounting evidence of participa- tion by doctors in interrogation by the security services, in spite of the fact that the terms of the Declaration of Tokyo (to which the IMA is a signatory) are clearly being breached. They even failed to take any action when one of their colleagues, a Palestinian doctor, was detained and ill-treated. The workshop at the end of this section of the conference decided on a number of measures which could be expected to improve the record of the health professionals coming into con- tact with evidence of torture. These included better education in ethics for students and doctors, mechanisms of reporting offences anonymously, and making video records of interroga- tions. The third brief section, which deals with the legal struggle against torture, begins with a history of torture in Israel, giving examples of confessions being extracted from Palestinian detainees by torture as early in the Occupation as 1968, when the very existence of the Shabak, the interro- gation organisation, was officially denied though it enjoyed a symbiotic relationship with the police, judiciary and elements of the medical profes- o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://jm e .b m j.co m / J M e d E th ics: first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /jm e .2 2 .4 .2 5 0 o n 1 A u g u st 1 9 9 6 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://jme.bmj.com/ work_eape37elcffkhapbg57zrvo45y ---- Illuminating the ‘Face’ of Justice: A Meta‐Analytic Examination of Leadership and Organizational Justice Illuminating the ‘Face’ of Justice: A Meta-Analytic Examination of Leadership and Organizational Justice Elizabeth P. Karam, Jinyu Hu, Robert B. Davison, Matthew Juravich, Jennifer D. Nahrgang, Stephen E. Humphrey and D. Scott DeRue Texas Tech University; University of Nevada, Reno; University of Kansas; The University of Akron; Arizona State University; Pennsylvania State University; University of Michigan ABSTRACT A significant body of research has described effective leader behaviours and has connected these behaviours to positive employee outcomes. However, this research has yet to be systematically integrated with organizational justice research to describe how leader behaviours inform justice perceptions. Therefore, we conduct a meta-analysis (k = 166, N = 46,034) to investigate how three types of leader behaviours (task, relational, and change) inform four dimensions of organizational justice (procedural, distributive, interpersonal, and informational) referenced to the leader and to the organization. Further, we examine the joint impact of leader behaviours and justice perceptions on social exchange quality (i.e., leader– member exchange), task performance, and job satisfaction. Our results suggest that leader behaviours differentially inform leader- and organization-focused justice perceptions, and the joint effect of leader behaviours and justice perceptions offer more nuanced explanations for outcomes. Keywords: Leader behaviours, organizational justice, meta-analysis, social exchange theory INTRODUCTION Leadership is one of the most studied phenomenon in management (Cascio and Aguinis, 2008), and an extensive body of research has examined the behaviours that contrib- ute to effective leadership (Dinh et al., 2014). For example, studies that have exam- ined task leader behaviours (i.e., transactional leadership, contingent reward, initiating structure) have articulated that effective leaders define roles, solve problems, and plan Journal of Management Studies 56:1 January 2019 doi: 10.1111/joms.12402 © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies Address for reprints: Elizabeth P. Karam, Rawls College of Business, Texas Tech University, 703 Flint Ave, Lubbock, TX 79409-2101 (elizabeth.karam@ttu.edu). mailto: mailto:elizabeth.karam@ttu.edu Illuminating the ‘Face’ of Justice 135 © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies activities (Bass, 1985; Burns, 1978; Podsakoff et al., 2006; Yukl, 2012). Research into relational leader behaviours (e.g., consideration, servant leadership, participative lead- ership) describe how leaders demonstrate support and develop followers (Fleishman, 1953; Greenleaf, 1977; Spreitzer, 2007; Yukl, 2012). Change leadership research (e.g., transformational, charismatic) has focused on how effective leaders inspire, develop a vision, and encourage innovation (Bass, 1985; Howell and Avolio, 1993; Yukl, 2012). The positive effects of leaders on employee attitudes and behaviours have been noted in numerous conceptual and meta-analytic reviews (e.g., DeRue et al., 2011; Gardner et al., 2010; Judge et al., 2004). Indeed, this body of research contains detailed descriptions of what leaders do and how they affect individual, team, and organizational performance outcomes. A significant stream of organizational justice research has also examined the role of the leader in employee assessments of (un)fair treatment (Colquitt et al., 2013; Rupp and Cropanzano, 2002; Rupp et al., 2014). This research has found that justice perceptions of the leader (i.e., supervisor- or leader-focused justice), rather than perceptions of other organizational entities (e.g., the organization itself), are most strongly related to employee outcomes (Colquitt et al., 2013; Rupp et al., 2014). This is not surprising given that an employee’s relationship with his or her leader ‘may be the single most powerful con- nection an employee can build in an organization’ (Hui et al., 2004, p. 233). Therefore, justice research has identified the leader as an important source of justice (thereby an- swering the question, who is responsible for the (un)just treatment?), yet this research has not adequately answered the question of what behaviours the leader engages in to inform justice perceptions. This has prompted Rupp and Aquino (2009) to suggest that justice research is ‘ripe for integrative application’ with other theories so that more specific guid- ance can be given to leaders about how to promote fairness in the workplace (p. 208). Hence, one purpose of this study is to integrate research on leader behaviours with organizational justice research to explicate the specific behaviours that leaders utilize to inform justice perceptions. In doing so, we attempt to provide greater focus to the ‘face’ (i.e., the leader) of justice. An increased understanding of the relationships between leader behaviours and jus- tice perceptions is important for two reasons. First, employee-leader relationships are often characterized as social exchange relationships and are distinguished from other forms of exchanges by having expectations of longer-term, interdependent interactions that generate trust, reciprocal behaviours, and high-quality relationships (Blau, 1964; Cropanzano and Mitchell, 2005; Mitchell et al., 2012). This dynamic, interactive re- lationship suggests that employees’ justice perceptions may not be based exclusively on the leader’s justice decisions, but that these perceptions may also be informed by a range of the leader’s role-relevant behaviours. For this reason, examining only leader-focused justice perceptions, particularly in relation to an explicit ‘event’ (e.g., a single episode such as a performance appraisal), fails to consider the broader task, relational, and change in- teractions between the leader and the employee and how these interactions may impact justice assessments. Second, studies that examine leader-focused justice commonly focus on research questions related to either (a) investigating the unique effects of leader-focused justice 136 E. P. Karam et al. © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies dimensions (i.e., procedural, distributive, interpersonal, informational justice) on organi- zational outcomes (e.g., Colquitt et al., 2013; Frazier et al., 2010), or (b) exploring how (un)fair treatment attributed to a leader is similar to or different from (un)fair treatment attributed to others (e.g., the organization; Lavelle et al., 2009; Liao and Rupp, 2005). This has produced a robust body of research informing scholars about which dimension of justice is most strongly related to specific organizational outcomes, and how leader- focused justice more strongly predicts affective and behavioural employee outcomes than justice attributed to other organizational entities (Colquitt et al., 2013; Rupp et al., 2014). However, research has neglected to explore the specific behaviours of the leader that relate to these justice dimensions. The second purpose of this study is to assess the joint effects of leadership and justice in explaining social exchange quality (i.e., leader-member exchange, LMX) and em- ployee outcomes (i.e., task performance and job satisfaction). Accumulated meta-an- alytic research to date has found that leader behaviours and justice perceptions have similar relationships with employee outcomes. For example, the effect size estimate for the relationship between leader-focused justice perceptions and task performance reported in a leader behaviour meta-analysis is .28 (Podsakoff et al., 2006), whereas organizational justice meta-analyses have reported this relationship to range from .16 to .27 (Colquitt et al., 2013; Rupp et al., 2014). Therefore, existing research has ex- amined the independent relationships of leader behaviours and justice perceptions with employee outcomes, but not the joint effects nor the relative importance of these predictors when considered together. This is a striking omission given that this exam- ination would provide a more comprehensive view of the effects of a leader’s decisions and behaviours. Thus, we integrate leadership research with organizational justice research to explore how leader behaviours inform justice perceptions. Then, we conduct a meta-analysis (k = 166, N = 46,034) to provide effect size estimates of the relationships between leader behaviours and justice dimensions, and we examine the joint effects of leadership and justice on LMX, task performance, and job satisfaction. We find that task, relational, and change leader behaviours differentially inform procedural, distributive, interpersonal, and informational justice perceptions. Additionally, combined leader behaviours and justice perceptions offer a more nuanced explanation for the relationships with social exchange quality and performance outcomes as compared to considering only the inde- pendent effects of leadership behaviours or justice on outcomes. Using meta-analysis for this study has several strengths including serving as a tool for theory development related to effective leader behaviours and organizational justice (Combs et al., 2011; Hunter and Schmidt, 2004). Therefore, we develop new theory that describes how leader behaviours have direct implications for justice perceptions. We point to the omission of, and the need for, current leadership theories to clearly ar- ticulate the importance of fairness in leader behaviours, and we describe how taking a more comprehensive view of the decisions and behaviours of the leader, by integrating leader behaviours and justice perceptions, is critical to accurately assessing the impact of a leader on employee outcomes. Illuminating the ‘Face’ of Justice 137 © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies THEORETICAL BACKGROUND One purpose of this meta-analysis is to investigate behaviours that inform leader- focused justice perceptions. We therefore examine leader behaviours that are related to four dimensions of organizational justice referenced to the leader (i.e., leader-focused distributive justice, leader-focused procedural justice, leader-focused interpersonal jus- tice, leader-focused informational justice; Colquitt, 2001; Colquitt et al., 2013). Further, given that leaders are often viewed as representatives of the organization (Eisenberger et al., 2010; Levinson, 1965), we also consider how leader behaviours affect percep- tions of organization-focused distributive justice and organization-focused procedural justice.1 The four dimensions of justice are based on distinct assessments of fairness in organizational decision-making. Perceptions of distributive justice, the perceived fairness of outcomes, are based on an employee comparing the ratio of his or her inputs and outcomes to the inputs and outcomes of referent others (Adams, 1965; Ambrose and Arnaud, 2005). Procedural justice suggests that individuals evaluate fairness not just on outcomes, but also on fairness in the decision-making process and the ability to have voice in this process (Levanthal, 1980; Thibaut and Walker, 1975, 1978). Interpersonal justice reflects fairness perceptions of interpersonal treatment, and informational justice reflects fairness perceptions of the adequacy and truthfulness of explanations (Colquitt, 2001; Greenberg, 1993). Justice research is grounded in social exchange theory (SET; Colquitt et al., 2013; Gouldner, 1960; Rupp and Cropanzano, 2002), and this theory provides an important basis for a contextual understanding of the leader-employee relationship. Social exchange relationships are characterized by a high frequency of interactions and task interdepen- dence. Additionally, a characteristic of SET is the notion of time – including knowl- edge of past actions and an expectation of future obligations (Blau, 1964; Gouldner, 1960). Colquitt et al. (2013) suggested that justice attributed to a particular source has expansive time bracketing, lacking a discrete beginning and end. Therefore, in a social exchange relationship, employees are not evaluating a justice ‘event’ but an ‘entity’ with whom the employee has considerable interactions. Indeed, Cropanzano and colleagues (2001) argued that the ‘key issue regarding the relationship paradigm is that respondents are judging the fairness of [the leader]… over time and/or across situations’ (p. 190). Consequently, perceptions of leader-focused justice are likely to take into account nu- merous decisions and behaviours made by the leader given the number of interpersonal exchanges in the relationship (Colquitt, 2008). Managerial role theory has identified decision-making as a key role requirement of leaders in organizations (Dierdorff et al., 2009; Mintzberg, 1973), and numerous scholars have maintained that decision-making is a core component of effective leader behaviours (e.g., Borman and Brush, 1993; Tett et al., 2000; Yukl, 2012). Examples of decision-making responsibilities include planning how to organize and prioritize work; determining how to allocate resources; and assigning responsibilities. Many of these decisions have fairness implications for employees. Employee justice perceptions, 138 E. P. Karam et al. © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies therefore, are likely to be based on observation and assessment of numerous leader de- cisions. To be precise, each leader decision provides employees with information to po- tentially (re-)assess the fairness of the leader as well as information to (re-)evaluate the effectiveness and competence of the leader (Masterson and Lensges, 2015). Employees, therefore, can both assess the behaviour and appraise the fairness of their leader in their interactions. As a result, we suggest that there is a reciprocal relationship between leader behaviours and justice perceptions and that both of these assessments can inform per- ceptions of the leader. However, decision-making is only one of several key role requirements for organiza- tional leaders. In fact, Yukl (2012) identified three meta-categories of effective leader behaviours based on an analysis of 50 years of research.2 The first meta-category, task leader behaviours, includes previous research on transactional leadership, initiating structure, and contingent reward behaviours (Bass, 1985; Burns, 1978; Fleishman, 1953). Task leader behaviours are focused on efficient use of resources, and they include plan- ning, solving problems, and monitoring progress toward goals (DeRue et al., 2011; Yukl et al., 2002). Task leader behaviours clearly convey information about expectations and standards to clarify employee responsibilities. Therefore, effective task leaders also em- phasize and make allocation decisions related to discretionary and formal rewards for job performance (Howell and Avolio, 1993). The second meta-category, relational leader behaviours, is focused on supporting, rec- ognizing, developing, and empowering individuals (Yukl, 2012). These leader behaviours demonstrate consideration, concern, respect, empathy, and socioemotional support for subordinates (Fleishman, 1953; Greenleaf, 1977). Effective relational behaviours negoti- ate conflict, encourage participation, and focus subordinate attention on group welfare in their own actions and decision making (Bass, 2008). Relational leaders also are par- ticipative in that they seek input from employees, and they treat all group members as equals (Brower et al., 2000). Finally, the third meta-category, change leader behaviours, is focused on facilitating and driving change and innovation within an organization (Yukl, 2012). Change leader behaviours include developing and communicating a vision for change; encouraging sub- ordinates to be creative and to take risks; and seeking alternate perspectives on challenges facing the group (Bass, 1985; Howell and Avolio, 1993). Several dimensions of transfor- mational leadership theory are included in effective change leader behaviours including charisma, inspirational motivation (i.e., inspiring employees to perform at high levels), intellectual stimulation, and idealized influence (Bass, 1985). Further, change leader be- haviours include upholding high ethical standards (Bass, 1985). The three categories of effective behaviours – task, relational, and change – involve distinct behaviours and decisions of a leader. Thus, these leader behaviours are expected to have different implications for justice perceptions. Therefore, we now turn to exam- ining how task, relational, and change leader behaviours uniquely inform procedural, distributive, interpersonal, and informational justice perceptions. Illuminating the ‘Face’ of Justice 139 © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies HYPOTHESES Leader Behaviours and Leader-Focused Procedural Justice The most prevalent area of leadership and justice research examines leader behaviours and procedural justice. Procedural justice refers to perceptions of fairness in decision making processes (Colquitt, 2001), and two dominant theories attempt to describe why employees are concerned with fair processes. The control theory perspective, also re- ferred to as the self-interest or instrumental model, argues that employees value voice in the decision-making process because of the potential connection to the resulting out- come (Thibaut and Walker, 1975, 1978). Levanthal (1980) further developed control theory by articulating six rules for fair procedures. These include the consistency rule whereby consistent decisions are made across time and persons. The bias suppression rule which suggests that the decision maker should remove personal biases/interests in the decision-making process. The accuracy rule relates to procedures being followed that are based on valid information. The correctability rule provides a mechanism to reverse a decision. The representativeness rule ensures that procedures ref lect the concerns of those impacted by the decision, and the ethicality rule ensures that decisions conform to moral and ethical standards. The second theoretical perspective, the relational model, proposes that there are psy- chological aspects of procedural justice that are not covered by control theory, and it argues that individuals care about procedural justice because of the relational messages communicated through fair processes (Blader and Tyler, 2015; Lind and Tyler, 1988). Therefore, fairness in the decision-making process matters not solely because of control or voice, but because it reaffirms group values and relational status in the decision-mak- ing process (Tyler and Blader, 2000). Tyler and Lind (1992) further suggest that people seek identity-relevant information through interactions with leaders and that when lead- ers demonstrate concern in the decision-making process, they convey socioemotional support as well as social standing through these interactions. Numerous empirical studies have found support for the combined effects of the control theory perspective and the relational model of procedural justice (e.g., Lind et al., 1990; Tyler, 1989). Based on employee concerns for both control and the relational messages conveyed in fair processes, two leader behaviour categories are most likely to inform perceptions of leader-focused procedural justice. First, effective task leader behaviours involve structur- ing tasks, standardizing procedures, and ensuring rules are followed in a systematic for- mat. These behaviours are likely to satisfy an individual’s control needs for consistency, bias suppression, accuracy, and correctability (Holtz and Harold, 2013). Second, effec- tive relational leader behaviours involve consulting employees about matters that affect them which conveys standing to employees as well as fulfilling their needs for representa- tiveness in the decision-making process (Yukl, 2012). Relational leaders also demonstrate consideration and support which affirms relational status (Holtz and Harold, 2013). Finally, relational leaders also regularly offer praise and recognition which signal group values and make employees feel that decisions are consistent (Ng, 2017). Conversely, change leader behaviours are focused on communicating and inspiring. Therefore, even though the ethical elements of change leader behaviours may be related to the ethicality 140 E. P. Karam et al. © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies rule, the majority of needs articulated in the control theory perspective are related to task leader behaviours rather than change leader behaviours. Hypothesis 1: Task (a) and relational (b) leader behaviours will exhibit a stronger pos- itive relationship with leader-focused procedural justice perceptions than change leader behaviours. Leader Behaviours and Organization-Focused Procedural Justice Levinson (1965) suggested that there is a transference process whereby employees de- velop a relationship with a leader and ascribe that relationship to the organization. Therefore, employees view leaders not only as ‘individuals in their own right’ but also as agents, or representatives of the organization (Eisenberger et al., 2010, p. 1086). This process suggests that perceptions of (un)fair treatment by the leader are likely to be viewed, at least partially, as (un)fair treatment by the organization. As such, employ- ees may view fairness and treatment in decision making processes through the lens of the leader acting as an embodiment of the organization because they generalize the decision and treatment from their leader to the organization (Cropanzano et al., 2001; Eisenberger et al., 2002; Stinglhamber et al., 2015). Given this, we suggest that effective task and relational leader behaviours will also inform organization-focused procedural justice perceptions and more so than the change leader behaviours following the ratio- nale described above. Hypothesis 2: Task (a) and relational (b) leader behaviours will exhibit a stronger pos- itive relationship with organization-focused procedural justice perceptions than change leader behaviours. Leader Behaviours and Leader-Focused Distributive Justice Distributive justice research is based in equity (Adams, 1965) and social exchange theo- ries (Blau, 1964). These theories position distributive justice as the perceived fairness of outcomes based on employees comparing ‘the ratio of their inputs and outcomes to the inputs and outcomes of referent others. Distributions are [deemed to be] fair to the ex- tent that rewards are proportionally matched to contributions’ (Ambrose and Arnaud, 2005, p. 61). Distributive justice perceptions are then based on equity norms of alloca- tion (Adams, 1965; Colquitt, 2001). Subsequent work by Levanthal (1980) described alternate reasons individuals care about distributive justice by calling attention to sev- eral issues with equity theory. First, he argued that equity theory took a unidimensional rather than multidimensional conception of fairness. That is, by focusing exclusively on the contribution (i.e., equity) rule, equity theory ignored other standards that could inf luence distributive justice perceptions including an employee’s psychological needs. Second, equity theory only considered the final outcome and not the organizational systems, policies, and practices that can lead to allocations (Levanthal, 1980). Numerous others echoed these criticisms. For example, Greenberg (1993) argued that the original Illuminating the ‘Face’ of Justice 141 © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies theorizing on distributive justice was too narrowly focused on structural matters at the expense of the social determinants of distributive fairness. Greenberg (1993) asserted that the ‘interpersonal aspects of justice – which thus far have been appreciated only from a procedural justice perspective – are also involved in the distributive side of jus- tice’ (p. 82). We acknowledge both the structural and more contemporary theorizing based on the personal and social determinants of distributive justice and assert that two leader be- haviour categories are most likely to inform perceptions of leader-focused distributive justice: task and change leader behaviours. Effective task leader behaviours involve allo- cating resources among different employees and activities (Yukl, 2012). Therefore, per- ceptions of distributive justice are likely to be enhanced based on the perceived fairness of these decisions. Further, task leader behaviours focus on contingent rewards whereby a leader promises specific rewards in exchange for performance (Bass, 1985). Hence, a clear link between employee efforts and rewards is established. Finally, task leader be- haviours aimed at initiating structure with standardized work environments and uniform performance guidelines should enhance employee perceptions that reward allocations are made equitably. In a similar vein, effective change leaders uphold high ethical stan- dards and make resource allocations decisions in a way that satisfies personal psycholog- ical needs related to equity (Cropanzano et al., 2001; Ng, 2017). That is, change leaders’ ‘moral values take into account the cost and benefits to all stakeholders, the application of distributive justice, and universal moral principles’ when confronting issues related to fairness (Bass, 1985, p. 218). This suggests that change leaders are not only aware of fairness issues, but they are adept at navigating these issues equitably. In contrast, the emphasis of relational leader behaviours is on supporting and recognizing employees which is not the focus of either the structural nor more contemporary theorizing on distributive justice. Hypothesis 3: Task (a) and change (b) leader behaviours will exhibit a stronger positive relationship with leader-focused distributive justice perceptions than relational leader behaviours. Leader Behaviours and Organization-Focused Distributive Justice As argued above, employees may view leaders as representatives of the organization; and therefore, leader behaviours may impact perceptions of organization-focused dis- tributive justice. Eisenberger et al. (2010) have specifically argued that both task (e.g., directive, evaluative, coaching) and change (e.g., developing and/or communicating a vision) leader behaviours are commonly viewed by employees as activities carried out on behalf of the organization. As a result, when a leader is conducting a performance evaluation, the employee may attribute some portion of the reward allocation decision to the policies, processes, or other structural aspects of the organization rather than exclusively to the leader. Similarly, by communicating a vision to encourage greater in- puts, the employee may view potential rewards as coming from the organization rather than exclusively the leader. Therefore, we suggest that effective task and change leader 142 E. P. Karam et al. © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies behaviours will inform organization-focused distributive justice perceptions as well, whereas relational behaviours are less likely to do so. Hypothesis 4: Task (a) and change (b) leader behaviours will exhibit a stronger positive relationship with organization-focused distributive justice perceptions than relational leader behaviours. Leader Behaviours and Interpersonal Justice Interpersonal justice focuses on perceptions of interpersonal interactions and the extent to which people are treated with respect when decisions are made and outcomes are determined (Colquitt et al., 2013). Holtz and Harold (2009) have described interpersonal justice as encounter-based in that the social exchange transactions between leaders and subordinates occur frequently. Therefore, they argue that interpersonal justice is more salient than other forms of justice. This is consistent with fairness heuristic theory, part of the relational model of justice, which suggests that subordinates make quick assess- ments of the fairness of their leaders based on initial justice encounters (Lind, 2001). Relational leaders are especially skilled at sensing the needs of subordinates and show- ing concern. They listen, provide support, and treat employees with dignity and respect (Bass, 1985; Yukl, 2012). As interpersonal treatment is promoted through respect, status, and showing concern for others, relational leader behaviours are most likely to inform perceptions of leader-focused interpersonal justice. Alternatively, whereas effective task (i.e., structuring tasks, directing activities, coaching) and change (i.e., communicating a vision, encouraging innovation, upholding high ethical standards) leader behaviours may be communicated in a manner that demonstrates respectful treatment, such treat- ment is not the primary focus of these behaviours. Hypothesis 5: Relational leader behaviours will exhibit a stronger positive relationship with interpersonal justice perceptions than will either task (a) or change (b) leader behaviours. Leader Behaviours and Informational Justice Informational justice ref lects fairness perceptions related to the comprehensiveness and truthfulness of explanations (Colquitt, 2001; Greenberg, 1993). It is also encoun- ter-based in that the frequency of interactions between leaders and subordinates in social exchange relationships offers employees numerous opportunities to assess the fairness of information provided. Effective change leader behaviours involve communicating why changes are necessary for employees (Bass, 1985), and the emphasis on open and com- prehensive communication in change leader behaviours allows employees to more fully understand decisions. Further, change leader behaviours encourage employees to seek alternate perspectives, and they promote intellectual stimulation which allows for greater comprehension of an explanation (Zhang et al., 2014). Finally, change leaders generally uphold high ethical standards which should enhance perceptions of the truthfulness Illuminating the ‘Face’ of Justice 143 © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies of the explanation (Bass, 1985). Conversely, task leader behaviours are focused on di- recting, coaching, clarifying responsibilities, and monitoring progress. Therefore, these behaviours have less of an emphasis on comprehensiveness of information conveyed and more of a transactional focus. Similarly, relational leader behaviours focus on recog- nizing and showing socioemotional support for employees which is more ref lective of empathic communications rather than comprehensive and truthful explanations. Hypothesis 6: Change leader behaviours will exhibit a stronger positive relationship with informational justice perceptions than will either task (a) or relational (b) leader behaviours. SOCIAL EXCHANGE QUALITY AND EMPLOYEE OUTCOMES The preceding section suggested how leader behaviours inform justice perceptions. We turn now to the second purpose of this study: discussing the joint impact of justice perceptions and leader behaviours in explaining social exchange quality and employee outcomes. Here, we also present a model that describes the nonrecursive nature (i.e., reciprocally interdependent; Bentler and Raykov, 2000) of perceptions of the leader (in- cluding both leader behaviours and justice perceptions) as they impact social exchange quality and performance outcomes (see Figure 1). Social Exchange Quality The quality of the social exchange relationship between a leader and subordinate is commonly assessed by examining LMX (Graen and Scandura, 1987; Liden and Maslyn, 1998). Studies have argued and found support for assertions that both justice perceptions and leader behaviours enhance the quality of social exchange directly or indirectly (e.g., Wayne et al., 2002). However, what is lacking from current research is a better understanding of which leader behaviours or justice dimensions have greater Figure 1. Conceptual model of organizational justice, effective leader behaviours, social exchange quality, and subordinate outcomes 144 E. P. Karam et al. © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies inf luence on LMX when considered jointly. The target similarity model in the orga- nizational justice literature predicts that there will be stronger relationships between target similar justice perceptions and outcomes (e.g., leader-focused justice➙perceived leader support➙leader-directed citizenship behaviour) than target dissimilar justice perceptions and outcomes (e.g., leader-focused justice➙perceived organizational sup- port➙organization-directed citizenship behaviour; Lavelle et al., 2007). Accordingly, leader-focused justice perceptions should have a stronger relationship with LMX than organization-focused just perceptions. Yet neither the target similarity model nor any theories of leadership specifically address how justice, combined with assessments of the leader’s behaviours, will inf luence social exchange quality. Therefore, given that these perceptions are based on numerous interactions with the focal leader, existing research has an incomplete understanding of the joint effects and relative importance of justice and leader behaviours in explaining LMX. Therefore, we pose the following research question: Research question 1: When considered simultaneously, what unique contributions do leader behaviours and justice dimensions make to explaining variance in LMX, and what is the relative important of these contributions? Task Performance and Job Satisfaction Extant research has demonstrated strong, positive relationships between both leader behaviours and justice perceptions and employee task performance and job satisfaction (Colquitt et al., 2013; DeRue et al., 2011; Podsakoff et al., 2006; Rupp et al., 2014). Indeed, the dominant focus of both leader behaviour and justice research has been the prediction of these outcomes. However, there are conf licting theoretical arguments as to whether leader behaviours or justice dimensions have greater inf luence on subordinate outcomes when considered jointly. For example, Kirkman et al. (2009) suggest that jus- tice will be a stronger predictor of outcomes, and they assert that leader behaviours are a ‘more distal and ambient stimuli’ than justice perceptions because leader behaviours are directed broadly to all individuals in a group (p. 748). Conversely, they argue that justice perceptions vary between individuals, and therefore are more proximal to (and will have a greater effect on) subordinate behaviours. An alternate argument proposed by De Cremer et al. (2007) suggests that leader behaviours exert a stronger inf luence on outcomes because justice practices simply create the essential conditions for leadership to emerge. That is, fair practices ‘create a psychological platform’ on which appraisals of leadership are built which motivate follower performance more directly (De Cremer et al., 2007, p. 1798). In other studies (e.g., Wayne et al., 2002), authors do not make predictions about whether leader behaviours or justice dimensions will have a greater impact on outcomes. Instead, they consider both as unique antecedents and do not ad- dress which is expected to have a greater effect on outcomes. Given this accumulation of research, and the divergence in theorizing related to the effects of leader behaviours and justice perceptions on subordinate outcomes, the Illuminating the ‘Face’ of Justice 145 © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies joint effect and relative importance of these predictors when considered simultaneously remains unclear. Therefore, we pose the following second research question: Research question 2: When considered simultaneously, what unique contributions do leader behaviours and justice dimensions make to explaining variance in (a) task performance and (b) job satisfaction, and what is the relative importance of these contributions? DATA AND METHODOLOGY Literature Search and Inclusion Criteria To identify empirical studies related to leader behaviours and organizational justice, we relied on several sources. First, we performed a literature search in four databases (PsycINFO, ISI Web of Science, Business Source Complete, and ProQuest Dissertations & Theses) for published studies, dissertations, and theses from 1900 to December 2017. The search was conducted using the term leader* as well as the justice-related keywords from Colquitt et al. (2001): procedural fairness, procedural justice, distributive fairness, distrib- utive justice, interactional justice, interpersonal treatment, interpersonal justice, informational jus- tice, and equity. Second, we searched for additional studies by sending emails through three Academy of Management (AOM) division listserves (Human Resources Division List, Network for Leadership Scholars, and Organizational Behavior Division List) re- questing published and unpublished studies that examined the relationship between leadership and organizational justice. Third, we searched the previous six years (i.e., 2012–17) of conference programs from the AOM and the Society for Industrial and Organizational Psychology to identify presented papers examining leader behaviours and organizational justice. Emails were then sent to the first authors of these conference papers requesting the unpublished manuscripts. These searches yielded an initial popu- lation of 760 studies to review for possible inclusion. Next, we examined these studies in detail to determine if they met the following inclusion rules established for this study. First, the study had to include both a leader- ship variable and an organizational justice variable. Second, the study had to report an effect size in a correlation matrix or other relevant information that could be used to calculate a zero-order correlation. Third, the study had to include a unique sample. If a sample was used in multiple studies, only one study was included; however, articles that included multiple studies with independent samples were coded separately. Fourth, we included only individual-level effect sizes and excluded group- or organizational-level data. Of the 760 studies in our initial population, 145 met all of these criteria, comprising 126 published studies, 19 unpublished manuscripts, and 166 independent samples (N = 46,034). Table I lists the primary studies coded for this meta-analysis. 146 E. P. Karam et al. © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies Table I. Studies included in the meta-analysis Academy of Management Journal Human Performance Erdogan et al. (2006) Johnson et al. (2009) Kirkman et al. (2009) Spector and Che (2014) Korsgaard et al. (1995) Human Relations Masterson et al. (2000) Cobb and Lau (2015) Tekleab et al. (2005) El Akremi et al. (2010) Tepper (2000) Keller and Dansereau (1995) Zhang et al. (2014) Murphy et al. (2003) Academy of Management Learning & Education International Journal of Contemporary Hospitality Management Graen et al. (2006) Dai et al. (2013) African Journal of Business Management International Journal of Hospitality Management Katrinli et al. (2010) Luo et al. (2014) Asian Journal of Social Psycholog y International Journal of Human Resource Management Jiang and Cheng (2008) Tuytens and Devos (2012) Australian Journal of Management Lee and Wei (2017) Georgalis et al. (2015) International Journal of Nursing Studies Brazilian Business Review Gillet et al. (2013) Cavazotte et al. (2013) International Journal of Sports Science & Coaching Decision Support Systems Kim and Andrew (2015) Tsay et al. (2014) International Journal of Stress Management Educational and Psychological Measurement Riolli and Savicki (2006) Kacmar et al. (1999) International Public Management Journal Employee Relations Potipiroon and Faerman (2016) Katou (2015) Journal of Applied Behavioral Science European Journal of Social Psycholog y Wu et al. (2007) De Cremer and den Ouden (2009) Journal of Applied Psycholog y European Journal of Work and Organizational Psycholog y Choi (2008) Colquitt (2001) De Cremer (2006) Colquitt et al. (2012) Gaudet et al. (2014) De Cremer and Van Knippenberg (2002) Mayer et al. (2008) De Cremer et al. (2005) Piccolo et al. (2008) Dineen et al. (2006) Sparr and Sonnentag (2008) Korsgaard et al. (2002) European Management Journal Rhoades et al. (2001) Grover and Coppins (2012) Thau and Mitchell (2010) Gender, Work and Organization Wayne et al. (2002) Cole (2004) Journal of Applied Social Psycholog y Group & Organization Management Cobb and Frey (1996) Camerman et al. (2007) De Cremer et al. (2007) Carter et al. (2014) Heck et al. (2005) Cropanzano et al. (2002) Lin et al. (2009) Frazier et al. (2010) (Continued) Illuminating the ‘Face’ of Justice 147 © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies Journal of Business and Psycholog y Journal of Personnel Psycholog y Burton et al. (2008) Camps et al. (2012) Tremblay et al. (2013) Journal of Social Psycholog y Walsh et al. (2018) Chi and Lo (2003) Journal of Business Ethics Leadership Chiaburu and Lim (2008) Kim and Kim (2015) Hsiung (2012) Leadership & Organization Development Journal Xu et al. (2016) Ansari et al. (2007) Journal of Business Research Bhal (2006) DeConinck (2010) Bhal and Ansari (2007) Gumusluoglu et al. (2013) Chiaburu and Marinova (2006) Journal of Experimental Social Psycholog y Fein et al. (2013) van Dijke and De Cremer (2010) Fuchs (2011) Journal of International Business Studies The Leadership Quarterly Pillai et al. (1999) Cho and Dansereau (2010) Journal of Leadership & Organizational Studies Haynie et al. (2014) Song et al. (2012) Sun et al. (2013) Strom et al. (2014) Walumbwa et al. (2008) Tremblay et al. (2018) Yang et al. (2009) Journal of Management Management and Organization Review Elicker et al. (2006) Chen et al. (2009) Karriker and Williams (2009) Li et al. (2014) Pillai et al. (1999) Wu et al. (2012) Roch and Shanock (2006) Military Psycholog y Rosen et al. (2011) Tremblay (2010) Journal of Marketing New Educational Review Netemeyer et al. (1997) Ishaq et al. (2012) Journal of Organizational Behavior Organization Science Andrews and Kacmar (2001) Hui et al. (2004) Aryee et al. (2002) Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes Epitropaki (2013) Johnson et al. (2006) Erdogan and Liden (2006) Lian et al. (2012) He et al. (2016) Martinko et al. (2007) Holtz and Harold (2013) van Dijke et al. (2012) Khazanchi and Masterson (2011) Walumbwa et al. (2011) Ogunfowora (2013) Personnel Psycholog y Walumbwa et al. (2009) Ehrhart (2004) Xu et al. (2012) Mansour-Cole and Scott (1998) Journal of Organizational Change Management Kool and van Dierendonck (2012) Table I (Continued ) (Continued) 148 E. P. Karam et al. © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies Data Coding As suggested by meta-analytic reporting standards (Kepes et al., 2013), the data coding process was guided by a set of protocols. First, we generated a list of leader behaviours and or- ganizational justice constructs guided by prior meta-analytic studies (Colquitt et al., 2001, 2013; DeRue et al., 2011; Rupp et al., 2014). If the study met the inclusion criteria above (i.e., contained both a leadership variable and a justice variable), we proceeded to code the correlations for the study variables. We articulated definitions for each of the coded constructs along with a list of common variable names to ensure consistency in coding among authors. An excel worksheet with macros was designated as the standard cod- ing sheet to capture relevant information defined by the protocols. This information included the measures, correlations, means, standard deviations, and reliabilities for all study variables. In addition, we captured the country where the data was collected, the context for the study (e.g., field, lab), and we noted whether the study was published or unpublished.3 Personnel Review Strategic Change Connell et al. (2003) Ferres et al. (2005) Tuytens and Devos (2012) Conference Papers Wat and Shaffer (2005) Rhodes et al. (2013) Psychological Reports Dissertations Tziner et al. (2008) Anand (2012) Procedia-Social and Behavioral Sciences Burlacu (2013) Zeinabadi and Rastegarpour (2010) Hoobler (2002) Public Administration Review Kiersch (2012) Hassan et al. (2014) Lam (2010) Public Management Review Li (2012) Gould-Williams and Davies (2005) Morrison (2015) Public Personnel Management Mosley (2006) Chen and Jin (2014) Oginde (2013) Review of Public Personnel Administration Ren (2008) Meng and Wu (2015) Roberts (2004) Revista De Psicología Del Trabajo Y De Las Organizaciones Sanchez (2006) Shalhoop (2004) Chernyak-Hai and Tziner (2014) Shull (1995) Service Industries Journal Simon (1995) Kang et al. (2012) White (2008) Social Behavior and Personality Williams (2012) Huang et al. (2015) Wilson (2011) Table I (Continued ) Illuminating the ‘Face’ of Justice 149 © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies Leader behaviours. Consistent with the definitions provided in Yukl (2012) and DeRue et al. (2011), correlations that included leader behaviours were coded as either task, relational, or change. Task leader behaviours are job-focused behaviours aimed at defining task roles and role relationships. They included initiating structure, contingent reward, and management by exception-active (DeRue et al., 2011). Relational leader behaviours focus on providing socioemotional support and demonstrating concern and respect. They include consideration (Bass, 1990), empowering leadership (Conger, 1989), and participative leadership (Kahai et al., 1997). Change leader behaviours are focused on developing and communicating a vision of change, encouraging innovation, and facilitating collective learning. They include the transformational leadership dimensions of charisma, inspirational motivation, intellectual stimulation, and idealized inf luence, and visionary leadership (Bass, 1985). Organizational justice. Following the protocols in existing meta-analyses (Colquitt et al., 2013; Rupp et al., 2014), we coded correlations that included justice variables by dimension (i.e., procedural, distributive, interpersonal, or informational ) and by source, the party referenced as the ‘deliverer’ of the (un)just treatment (leader-focused or organization- focused ). We determined the type and source by examining the specif ic scale item(s) and item instructions in the method section. Consistent with the coding details provided by Rupp et al. (2014), we found that justice type was most often labeled explicitly whereas justice source was not. Therefore, again following the coding protocol of Rupp et al. (2014), when information about the source of justice in the method section was ambiguous, we would review the theoretical arguments and hypotheses to make a coding determination about the justice source. In the case of conf licting information about the source between the method and theory sections, we used the source def ined by the scale items or instructions. Our f inal dataset consists of correlations with six justice variables: leader-focused procedural justice, leader-focused distributive justice, (leader-focused) interpersonal justice, (leader-focused) informational justice, organization-focused procedural justice, and organization- focused distributive justice. Social exchange quality and subordinate outcomes.4 To capture the social exchange quality between the leader and subordinate, we coded bivariate correlations with LMX as a leader-referent social exchange variable (Graen and Scandura, 1987; Liden and Maslyn, 1998). We also coded correlations that included two subordinate outcome variables – one behavioural outcome (i.e., task performance) and one affective outcome (i.e., job satisfaction). Task performance ref lects activities that contribute to the production of goods or provisions of services and that are commonly ref lected in formal job requirements (Rotundo and Sackett, 2002); and job satisfaction captures the positive cognitive or affective emotional response to one’s job (Hulin and Judge, 2003). Consistent with prior research, we conceptualized task performance as a leader-directed outcome variable and job satisfaction as a global, organization-directed outcome variable for purposes of comparing findings with the target similarity model (Cropanzano et al., 2002; Rupp and Cropanzano, 2002; Rupp et al., 2014). 150 E. P. Karam et al. © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies ANALYSIS AND RESULTS Analytical Procedures We used the procedures recommended by Hunter and Schmidt (2004) in conducting the meta-analysis. We corrected for sampling error and for measurement unreliability in the reported correlations using the Cronbach’s alpha statistics reported in the study. In the small number of cases where reliability information for a variable was not reported, we employed the average reliability of all other studies that did report reliability data for that variable (Hunter and Schmidt, 2004). In addition, several studies reported multiple estimates of the same bivariate relationship (e.g., procedural justice and LMX). For these cases, we created a composite correlation for the relationship of interest (Colquitt et al., 2013; Hunter and Schmidt, 2004). We report the results of the meta-analysis for the rela- tionships between leader behaviours and referent-specific justice dimensions in Table II. For each bivariate relationship, we report the number of studies (k); the sample size (N ); the uncorrected (ρu) population correlation and the 95% confidence interval (CI) around this value; the corrected (ρc) population correlation and the 80% credibility interval (CV) around this value; the standard deviation of the corrected population correlation (SD-ρc); the percentage of variance in each population correlation explained by study artifacts (%Vart); and the homogeneity test score (Q ). Further, as biases may exist in our effect estimates due to selective publication of studies, we conducted Duval and Tweedie’s (2000) nonparametric ‘trim and fill’ analyses of publication bias employing the metatrim command in Stata (Steichen, 2000). We report the additional imputed studies (Δk) and the adjusted population correlation (adj-ρc) resulting from this analysis in Table II. To analyse the hypotheses, we first created a meta-analytically derived correlation matrix for all variables in the study using our coded data. Then, we compared the me- ta-analytic corrected population correlations from this study to published meta-analytic estimates. Where published meta-analytic data was available, we replaced the value in our original data with the published corrected correlation in subsequent analyses unless our data had a higher k and N than the published data. In these cases, we retained our original data.5 The meta-analytic source of the substitutions and the meta-analytic val- ues are presented in Tables III, IV respectively. Employing the resultant meta-analytic correlation matrix, we conducted a dominance analysis (DA) for each hypothesis to investigate the relative importance of leader be- haviours in predicting justice perceptions (Budescu, 1993). DA is a qualitative compari- son of the relative importance of predictors in multiple linear regression (MLR), and it is robust to issues of multicolinearity because the approach is based on a predictor’s added predictive ability in the presence of other predictors. Further, it is more ‘sensitive to the various importance patterns that can emerge’ relative to other analytic techniques (Azen and Budescu, 2003, p. 124). Thus, DA is a superior statistical approach to assessing the relative importance of variables, particularly with a set of correlated predictors (Azen and Budescu, 2003). By using DA, we are able to infer which variables are dominant predictors of outcomes when considered in combination with other predictors. DA calculates and employs the squared multiple correlations of all possible MLR mod- els involving the predictors (2p – 1 models; p = number of predictors) to rank order Illuminating the ‘Face’ of Justice 151 © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies T a b le I I. M et a- an al yt ic c or re la ti on s am on g le ad er b eh av io u rs a n d re fe re n t- sp ec if ic d im en si on s of o rg an iz at io n al ju st ic e V ar ia bl e k N ρ u 95 % C I ρ c 80 % C V SD -ρ c % V ar t Q Δ k ad j- ρ c L ea de r- fo cu se d pr oc ed ur al ju st ic e T as k le ad er b eh av io u rs 10 2, 53 4 .5 4 [. 4 8 , . 61 ] .6 4 [. 4 6 , . 82 ] .1 4 11 .6 6% 85 .7 6 0 N C R el at io n al le ad er b eh av io u rs 15 3, 4 69 .5 3 [. 4 4, .6 1] .6 0 [. 38 , . 82 ] .1 7 8 .9 4% 16 7. 75 0 N C C h an ge le ad er b eh av io u rs 23 5, 58 0 .5 2 [. 4 6 , . 58 ] .6 0 [. 37 , . 82 ] .1 7 8 .7 9% 26 1. 75 0 N C O rg an iz at io n- fo cu se d pr oc ed ur al ju st ic e T as k le ad er b eh av io u rs 9 6 ,8 30 .2 7 [.1 1, .4 2] .3 2 [- .0 2, .6 6 ] .2 6 2. 37 % 37 9. 21 3 .1 8 R el at io n al le ad er b eh av io u rs 5 2, 26 6 .6 3 [. 54 , . 71 ] .7 2 [. 61 , . 8 4] .0 9 11 .6 7% 42 .8 4 0 N C C h an ge le ad er b eh av io u rs 12 5, 01 4 .5 6 [. 49 , . 63 ] .6 2 [. 4 4, . 8 0] .1 4 6 .7 1% 17 8 .7 7 0 N C L ea de r- fo cu se d di st ri bu ti ve ju st ic e T as k le ad er b eh av io u rs 8 1, 65 3 .4 4 [. 36 , . 52 ] .4 9 [. 36 , . 62 ] .1 0 27 .5 8% 29 .0 1 0 N C R el at io n al le ad er b eh av io u rs 5 78 4 .3 6 [. 25 , . 47 ] .4 3 [. 26 , . 6 0] .1 3 27 .3 5% 18 .2 8 0 N C C h an ge le ad er b eh av io u rs 10 2, 0 87 .3 6 [. 26 , . 4 6 ] .4 0 [. 21 , . 59 ] .1 5 17 .7 5% 56 .3 3 0 N C O rg an iz at io n- fo cu se d di st ri bu ti ve ju st ic e T as k le ad er b eh av io u rs 8 6 ,5 32 .2 9 [.1 1, .4 8] .3 5 [- .0 5, .7 5] .3 1 1. 49 % 53 5. 6 6 5 .1 5 R el at io n al le ad er b eh av io u rs 5 2, 22 7 .5 3 [. 41 , . 65 ] .5 8 [. 39 , . 77 ] .1 5 6 .3 2% 79 .0 9 0 N C C h an ge le ad er b eh av io u rs 6 3, 03 2 .5 1 [. 36 , . 67 ] .5 9 [. 29 , . 89 ] .2 4 2. 45 % 24 4. 81 0 N C In te rp er so na l j us ti ce T as k le ad er b eh av io u rs 9 1, 55 9 .4 9 [. 42 , . 56 ] .5 4 [. 43 , . 6 6 ] .0 9 35 .0 1% 25 .7 1 0 N C R el at io n al le ad er b eh av io u rs 6 91 8 .5 1 [. 4 0, .6 3] .6 0 [. 4 0, . 8 0] .1 5 17 .0 0% 35 .2 9 0 N C C h an ge le ad er b eh av io u rs 6 1, 4 03 .5 5 [. 50 , . 59 ] .6 0 [. 57 , . 63 ] .0 3 77 .4 0% 7. 75 1 .5 9 In fo rm at io na l j us ti ce T as k le ad er b eh av io u rs 8 1, 4 85 .5 8 [. 49 , . 6 6 ] .6 4 [. 49 , . 8 0] .1 2 18 .1 7% 4 4. 0 4 3 .6 0 R el at io n al le ad er b eh av io u rs 5 79 9 .5 6 [. 43 , . 69 ] .6 6 [. 47 , . 85 ] .1 5 15 .6 6% 31 .9 2 1 .6 3 C h an ge le ad er b eh av io u rs 3 97 1 .6 8 [. 63 , . 73 ] .7 5 [. 75 , . 75 ] .0 0 10 0. 0 0% 2. 99 1 .7 4 N ot es : k = n u m b er o f s tu d ie s; N = s am p le s iz e; ρ u = u n co rr ec te d p op u la ti on c or re la ti on ; 9 5% C I = co n fi d en ce in te rv al a ro u n d u n co rr ec te d p op u la ti on c or re la ti on ; ρ c = c or re ct ed p op u la ti on c or re la ti on ; 8 0 % C V = c re d ib il it y in te rv al a ro u n d w ei gh te d co rr ec te d m ea n c or re la ti on ; S D -ρ c = s ta n d ar d d ev ia ti on o f t h e co rr ec te d p op u la ti on c or re la ti on ; % V ar t = p er ce n ta ge o f va ri an ce i n ρ c ex p la in ed b y st u d y ar ti fa ct s; Δ k = n u m b er o f fi lle d st u d ie s in t ri m a n d fi ll an al ys is ; ad j- ρ c = a d ju st ed ρ c af te r ad d in g fi lle d st u d ie s in t ri m a n d fi ll an al ys is ; N C = n o ch an ge i n a d ju st ed ρ c fr om t ri m a n d fi ll an al ys is . 152 E. P. Karam et al. © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies T a b le I II . S ou rc e of c or re la ti on s am on g st ud y va ri ab le s fo r d om in an ce a n al ys es V a ri a b le 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 1. T as k le ad er b eh av io u rs 2. R el at io n al le ad er b eh av io u rs N ew 3. C h an ge le ad er b eh av io u rs N ew D et al 11 4. P J- le ad er N ew N ew N ew 5. P J- or ga n iz at io n N ew N ew N ew N ew 6 . D J- le ad er N ew N ew N ew N ew N ew 7. D J- or ga n iz at io n N ew N ew N ew N ew N ew N ew 8 . In te rp er so n al ju st ic e N ew N ew N ew N ew N ew N ew N ew 9. In fo rm at io n al ju st ic e N ew N ew N ew N ew N ew N ew N ew N ew 10 . L M X G & A 16 G & A 16 D et al 12 N ew N ew N ew N ew N ew N ew 11 . T as k p er fo rm an ce P et al 0 6 W & L 93 N 17 C et al 13 C et al 13 C et al 13 C et al 13 C et al 13 C et al 13 M et al 16 12 . Jo b sa ti sf ac ti on JP I0 4 JP I0 4 N 17 N ew N ew N ew N ew N ew N ew D et al 12 Je ta l0 1 N ot es : P J- le ad er = le ad er -f oc u se d pr oc ed u ra l ju st ic e; P J- or ga n iz at io n = or ga n iz at io n -f oc u se d pr oc ed u ra l ju st ic e; D J- le ad er = le ad er -f oc u se d d is tr ib ut iv e ju st ic e; D J- or ga n iz at io n = o rg an iz at io n -f oc u se d d is tr ib ut iv e ju st ic e. N ew = d at a or ig in al t o th is s tu d y; D et al 11 = D eR u e et a l. (2 01 1) ; G & A 16 = G ot tf re d so n a n d A gu in is ( 20 16 ); D et al 12 = D u le b oh n e t al . ( 20 12 ); P et al 0 6 = P od sa ko ff e t al . ( 20 0 6) ; W & L 93 = W of fo rd a n d L is ka (1 9 93 ); N 17 = N g (2 01 7 ); C et al 13 = C ol q u it t et a l. (2 01 3) ; M et al 16 = M ar ti n et a l. (2 01 6) ; J P I0 4 = J u d ge e t al . ( 20 0 4) ; J et al 01 = J u d ge e t al . ( 20 01 ). Illuminating the ‘Face’ of Justice 153 © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies T a b le I V . M et a- an al yt ic e st im at es o f c or re la ti on s am on g st ud y va ri ab le s 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 ρ c ρ c ρ c ρ c ρ c ρ c ρ c ρ c ρ c ρ c ρ c k; N k; N k; N k; N k; N k; N k; N k; N k; N k; N k; N 1. T as k le ad er b eh av io u rs 2. R el at io n al le ad er .7 2 b eh av io u rs 11 ; 3 ,2 36 3. C h an ge le ad er .6 3 .7 1 b eh av io u rs 15 ; 6 ,7 4 4 8 , 1 ,0 74 4. P J- le ad er .6 4 .6 0 .6 0 10 ; 2 ,5 34 15 ; 3 ,4 69 23 ; 5 ,5 8 0 5. P J- or ga n iz at io n .3 2 .7 2 .6 2 .6 4 9; 6 ,8 30 5; 2 ,2 6 6 12 ; 5 ,0 14 6; 1 ,6 9 4 6 . D J- le ad er .4 9 .4 3 .4 0 .6 2 .5 1 8; 1 ,6 53 5; 7 8 4 10 ; 2 ,0 87 33 ; 5 ,5 0 6 4; 6 69 7. D J- or ga n iz at io n .3 5 .5 8 .5 9 .4 4 .6 9 .6 0 8; 6 ,5 32 5; 2 ,2 27 6; 3 ,0 32 19 ; 1 0, 63 9 10 9; 5 8 ,5 29 2; 3 41 8 . In te rp er so n al .5 4 .6 0 .6 0 .6 2 .6 5 .5 0 .4 1 ju st ic e 9; 1 ,5 59 6; 9 18 6; 1 ,4 03 12 ; 2 ,2 81 29 ; 1 2, 8 65 10 ; 1 ,7 50 25 ; 6 ,8 25 9. In fo rm at io n al .6 4 .6 6 .7 5 .7 5 .6 0 .6 0 .4 9 .7 7 ju st ic e 8; 1 ,4 85 5; 7 99 3; 9 71 10 ; 1 ,9 58 16 ; 4 ,0 6 8 8; 1 ,3 77 15 ; 4 ,0 33 31 ; 7 ,1 42 10 . L M X .6 6 .7 4 .7 3 .5 6 .4 9 .4 2 .4 2 .6 2 .6 3 22 ; 5 ,9 73 23 ; 6 ,2 0 9 20 ; 5 ,4 51 29 ; 4 ,8 0 0 35 ; 8 ,6 99 25 ; 3 ,5 69 33 ; 8 ,8 19 16 ; 4 ,2 0 8 12 ; 2 ,9 43 11 . T as k p er fo rm an ce .2 8 .2 5 .2 7 .2 4 .2 0 .2 3 .2 0 .1 6 .2 6 .3 0 17 ; 6 ,1 8 0 36 ; 2 ,6 51 59 ; 1 4, 17 8 13 ; 2 ,6 8 6 42 ; 1 0, 07 5 8; 1 ,8 6 6 30 ; 6 ,9 9 0 11 ; 3 ,5 42 7; 1 ,4 62 14 6; 3 2, 67 0 12 . Jo b sa ti sf ac ti on .2 2 .4 6 .4 8 .4 6 .4 7 .5 3 .4 1 .4 1 .4 6 .4 9 .3 0 72 ; 1 0, 31 7 76 ; 1 1, 37 4 81 ; 3 2, 35 5 18 ; 2 ,5 34 28 ; 2 ,8 20 15 ; 1 ,9 81 30 ; 4 ,6 0 9 7; 1 ,0 19 6; 1 ,0 42 8 8; 2 2, 52 0 31 2; 5 4, 47 1 N ot es : P J- le ad er = le ad er -f oc u se d pr oc ed u ra l j u st ic e; P J- or ga n iz at io n = o rg an iz at io n -f oc u se d pr oc ed u ra l j u st ic e; D J- le ad er = le ad er -f oc u se d d is tr ib ut iv e ju st ic e; D J- or ga n iz at io n = o rg an iz at io n -f oc u se d d is tr ib ut iv e ju st ic e; ρ c = c or re ct ed p op u la ti on c or re la ti on ; k = n u m b er o f s tu d ie s; N = s am p le s iz e. 154 E. P. Karam et al. © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies predictors by their relative contribution to total variance explained. (A variety of software packages – e.g., the ‘yhat’ package in R: https://cran.r-project.org/web/packages/yhat/ index.html – are available to conduct a DA; see Nimon and Oswald, 2013.) The degree to which a focal predictor dominates other predictors is determined by examining the in- cremental variance explained across the models (Azen and Budescu, 2003). DA ‘indicates whether one IV contributes more unique variance than another IV, either (a) across all possible MLR submodels (i.e., complete dominance) or (b) on average across models of all-possible-subset sizes (i.e., conditional dominance); averaging conditional dominance weights yields general dominance weights’ (Nimon and Oswald, 2013, p. 652). Complete dominance occurs when the incremental variance explained by a focal pre- dictor is greater in all possible MLR models than that of the comparison predictor(s). Conditional dominance occurs when the average incremental variance explained by a focal predictor within each model size (i.e., averaged across the subset of models with the same number of predictors) is greater than that of the comparison predictor(s). General dominance occurs when the average of all conditional dominance measures (i.e., aver- age of the average for each model size) for a focal predictor is greater than that of the comparison predictor(s). Notably, the relative weight measure epsilon (Johnson, 2000) reported in many meta-analyses (e.g., DeRue et al., 2011) is an approximation of the general dominance measure. Dominance types are nested based on the strictness of the type’s definition: general under conditional and conditional under complete. Because each hypothesis has three leader behaviour predictor variables, there are seven subset models and three subset model sizes for each justice criterion. The research questions presented in this study attempt to determine the relative im- portance of leader behaviours and justice variables in explaining LMX, task perfor- mance, and job satisfaction. Here again, we employed DA to examine the rank order of predictor variables (Azen and Budescu, 2003; Budescu, 1993). Each research question had three leader behaviour and six justice predictor variables resulting in 511 subset models and nine subset model sizes for each outcome criterion. RESULTS Hypotheses 1–6 were concerned with the relationships between leader behaviours and dimensions of organizational justice (see Tables V‒VIII). Specifically, Hypothesis 1a pre- dicted that task leader behaviours would have a stronger positive relationship with lead- er-focused procedural justice than change leader behaviours. In support of this, we find that task leader behaviours completely dominate change leader behaviours (i.e., incremen- tal variance explained is greatest for task leader behaviours in all comparison models; see Table V, average ΔR2 = .19 > .15). Therefore, Hypothesis 1a was supported. Hypothesis 1b predicted that relational leader behaviours would have a stronger positive relationship with leader-focused procedural justice than change leader behaviours. Contrary to this hypoth- esis, change leader behaviours exhibit general dominance over relational leader behaviours (see Table V, average ΔR2 = .15 > .14). Therefore, Hypothesis 1b was not supported. Hypothesis 2a predicted that task leader behaviours would have a stronger, positive relationship with organization-focused procedural justice than change leader behaviours. https://cran.r-project.org/web/packages/yhat/index.html https://cran.r-project.org/web/packages/yhat/index.html Illuminating the ‘Face’ of Justice 155 © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies T a b le V . D om in an ce a n al ys is fo r le ad er b eh av io u rs p re d ic ti n g le ad er - an d or ga n iz at io n -f oc u se d pr oc ed u ra l j u st ic e M od el s iz e Su bs et m od el s C ri te ri on : L ea de r- fo cu se d pr oc ed ur al ju st ic e C ri te ri on : O rg an iz at io n- fo cu se d pr oc ed ur al ju st ic e T as k R el at io na l C ha ng e T as k R el at io na l C ha ng e Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k k = 0 a ve ra ge (n u ll ) 3 .4 1 1 .3 6 2 .3 6 2 .1 0 3 .5 2 1 .3 8 2 k = 1 a ve ra ge 3 .1 0 1 .0 5 3 .0 6 2 .0 4 3 .3 3 1 .1 6 2 k = 2 a ve ra ge 1 .0 6 1 .0 1 3 .0 3 2 .1 1 2 .2 6 1 .0 5 3 O ve ra ll av er ag e .1 9 1 .1 4 3 .1 5 2 .0 9 3 .3 7 1 .2 0 2 M od el R 2 .4 8 .6 5 N ot es : Δ R 2 = a ve ra ge i n cr em en ta l va ri an ce e xp la in ed b y ad d in g fo ca l le ad er b eh av io u r as a p re d ic to r to s u b se t m od el s of s iz e k, w h er e k = n u m b er o f ot h er p re d ic to rs i n t h e su b se t m od el . R an k = r an k or d er o f p re d ic to r in t er m s of r el at iv e im p or ta n ce i n p re d ic ti n g cr it er io n ( b as ed o n a ve ra ge i n cr em en ta l v ar ia n ce e xp la in ed , Δ R 2 ) . O ve ra ll av er ag e re pr es en ts t h e av er ag ed a d d it io n al c on tr ib ut io n t o va ri an ce e xp la in ed e ac h le ad er b eh av io u r ac ro ss a ll su b se t m od el s iz es (i .e ., av er ag e of a ll co n d it io n al v al u es ). T a b le V I. D om in an ce a n al ys is fo r le ad er b eh av io u rs p re d ic ti n g le ad er - an d or ga n iz at io n -f oc u se d d is tr ib ut iv e ju st ic e M od el s iz e Su bs et m od el s C ri te ri on : L ea de r- fo cu se d di st ri bu ti ve ju st ic e C ri te ri on : O rg an iz at io n- fo cu se d di st ri bu ti ve ju st ic e T as k R el at io na l C ha ng e T as k R el at io na l C ha ng e Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k k = 0 a ve ra ge (n u ll ) 3 .2 4 1 .1 8 2 .1 6 3 .1 2 3 .3 4 2 .3 5 1 k = 1 a ve ra ge 3 .0 8 1 .0 3 2 .0 2 3 .0 1 3 .1 4 2 .1 5 1 k = 2 a ve ra ge 1 .0 5 1 .0 0 3 .0 1 2 .0 3 3 .0 8 2 .0 8 1 O ve ra ll av er ag e .1 3 1 .0 7 2 .0 6 3 .0 5 3 .1 8 2 .1 9 1 M od el R 2 .2 6 .4 3 N ot es : Δ R 2 = a ve ra ge i n cr em en ta l va ri an ce e xp la in ed b y ad d in g fo ca l le ad er b eh av io u r as a p re d ic to r to s u b se t m od el s of s iz e k, w h er e k = n u m b er o f ot h er p re d ic to rs i n t h e su b se t m od el . R an k = r an k or d er o f p re d ic to r in t er m s of r el at iv e im p or ta n ce i n p re d ic ti n g cr it er io n ( b as ed o n a ve ra ge i n cr em en ta l v ar ia n ce e xp la in ed , Δ R 2 ) . O ve ra ll av er ag e re pr es en ts t h e av er ag ed a d d it io n al c on tr ib ut io n t o va ri an ce e xp la in ed o f e ac h le ad er b eh av io u r ac ro ss a ll su b se t m od el s iz es (i .e ., av er ag e of a ll co n d it io n al v al u es ). 156 E. P. Karam et al. © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies T a b le V II . D om in an ce a n al ys is fo r le ad er b eh av io u rs p re d ic ti n g in te rp er so n al a n d in fo rm at io n al ju st ic e M od el s iz e Su bs et m od el s C ri te ri on : I nt er pe rs on al ju st ic e C ri te ri on : I nf or m at io na l j us ti ce T as k R el at io na l C ha ng e T as k R el at io na l C ha ng e Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k k = 0 a ve ra ge (n u ll ) 3 .2 9 3 .3 6 1 .3 6 1 .4 1 3 .4 4 2 .5 6 1 k = 1 a ve ra ge 3 .0 3 3 .0 8 2 .0 9 1 .0 5 3 .0 6 2 .1 8 1 k = 2 a ve ra ge 1 .0 1 3 .0 3 2 .0 5 1 .0 2 2 .0 1 3 .1 2 1 O ve ra ll av er ag e .1 1 3 .1 5 2 .1 6 1 .1 6 3 .1 7 2 .2 9 1 M od el R 2 .4 3 .6 2 N ot es : Δ R 2 = a ve ra ge i n cr em en ta l va ri an ce e xp la in ed b y ad d in g fo ca l le ad er b eh av io u r as a p re d ic to r to s u b se t m od el s of s iz e k, w h er e k = n u m b er o f ot h er p re d ic to rs i n t h e su b se t m od el . R an k = r an k or d er o f p re d ic to r in t er m s of r el at iv e im p or ta n ce i n p re d ic ti n g cr it er io n ( b as ed o n a ve ra ge i n cr em en ta l v ar ia n ce e xp la in ed , Δ R 2 ) . O ve ra ll av er ag e re pr es en ts t h e av er ag ed a d d it io n al c on tr ib ut io n t o va ri an ce e xp la in ed b y ea ch le ad er b eh av io u r ac ro ss a ll su b se t m od el s iz es (i .e ., av er ag e of a ll co n d it io n al v al u es ). Illuminating the ‘Face’ of Justice 157 © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies T a b le V II I. D om in an ce a n al ys is fo r le ad er b eh av io u rs a n d le ad er - an d or ga n iz at io n -f oc u se d ju st ic e pr ed ic ti n g L M X M od el s iz e Su bs et m od el s C ri te ri on : L M X T as k R el at io na l C ha ng e P J- L dr P J- O rg D J- L dr D J- O rg IJ In fo J Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k k = 0 a ve ra ge (n u ll ) 9 .4 4 3 .5 5 1 .5 3 2 .3 1 6 .2 4 7 .1 8 8 .1 8 8 .3 8 5 .4 0 4 k = 1 a ve ra ge 36 .1 7 3 .2 5 1 .2 3 2 .0 7 6 .0 4 7 .0 2 9 .0 2 8 .1 2 4 .1 1 5 k = 2 a ve ra ge 8 4 .1 0 3 .1 6 1 .1 5 2 .0 2 6 .0 2 7 .0 1 9 .0 1 8 .0 6 4 .0 4 5 k = 3 a ve ra ge 12 6 .0 6 3 .1 2 1 .1 1 2 .0 1 7 .0 1 6 .0 0 9 .0 1 8 .0 4 4 .0 2 5 k = 4 a ve ra ge 12 6 .0 4 3 .0 9 1 .0 9 2 .0 0 8 .0 1 5 .0 0 9 .0 1 7 .0 3 4 .0 1 6 k = 5 a ve ra ge 8 4 .0 2 4 .0 8 1 .0 7 2 .0 0 9 .0 1 5 .0 0 7 .0 0 6 .0 3 3 .0 0 8 k = 6 a ve ra ge 36 .0 1 5 .0 7 1 .0 7 2 .0 0 9 .0 2 4 .0 1 6 .0 0 7 .0 3 3 .0 0 8 k = 7 a ve ra ge 9 .0 1 7 .0 7 1 .0 7 2 .0 0 8 .0 2 4 .0 1 5 .0 0 9 .0 3 3 .0 1 6 k = 8 a ve ra ge 1 .0 1 7 .0 8 1 .0 8 2 .0 1 8 .0 4 4 .0 1 6 .0 0 9 .0 4 3 .0 2 5 O ve ra ll av er ag e .1 0 3 .1 6 1 .1 6 2 .0 5 6 .0 5 7 .0 3 8 .0 3 9 .0 9 4 .0 7 5 M od el R 2 .7 2 N ot es : P J- L d r = l ea d er -f oc u se d pr oc ed u ra l ju st ic e; P J- O rg = o rg an iz at io n -f oc u se d pr oc ed u ra l ju st ic e; D J- L d r = l ea d er -f oc u se d d is tr ib ut iv e ju st ic e; D J- O rg = o rg an iz at io n - fo cu se d d is tr ib ut iv e ju st ic e; I J = i n te rp er so n al j u st ic e; I n fo J = i n fo rm at io n al j u st ic e. Δ R 2 = a ve ra ge i n cr em en ta l v ar ia n ce e xp la in ed b y ad d in g fo ca l v ar ia b le a s a pr ed ic to r to su b se t m od el s of s iz e k, w h er e k = n u m b er o f o th er p re d ic to rs i n t h e su b se t m od el . R an k = r an k or d er o f p re d ic to r in t er m s of r el at iv e im p or ta n ce i n p re d ic ti n g cr it er io n ( b as ed on a ve ra ge i n cr em en ta l va ri an ce e xp la in ed , Δ R 2 ) . O ve ra ll av er ag e re pr es en ts t h e av er ag ed a d d it io n al c on tr ib ut io n t o va ri an ce e xp la in ed b y ea ch p re d ic to r ac ro ss a ll su b se t m od el s iz es (i .e ., av er ag e of a ll co n d it io n al v al u es ). 158 E. P. Karam et al. © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies Contrary to this hypothesis, change leader behaviours exhibit general dominance over task leader behaviours (see Table V, average ΔR2 = .20 > .09). Therefore, Hypothesis 2a was not supported. Hypothesis 2b predicted that relational leader behaviours would have a stronger, positive relationship with organization-focused procedural justice than change leader behaviours. In support of this, we find that relational leader behaviours exhibit complete dominance (i.e., incremental variance explained is greatest for rela- tional leader behaviours in all comparison models; see Table V, average ΔR2 = .37 > .20). Therefore, Hypothesis 2b was supported. Notably, the model R2 for leader-focused procedural justice (.48) was less than for organization-focused procedural justice (.65). We return to this in the discussion section. Hypothesis 3a predicted that task leader behaviours would have a stronger, positive relationship with leader-focused distributive justice than relational leader behaviours. In support of this, we find that task leader behaviours completely dominate relational leader behaviours (i.e., incremental variance explained is greatest for task leader behaviours in all comparison models; see Table VI average ΔR2 = .13 > .07). Therefore, Hypothesis 3a was supported. Hypothesis 3b predicted that change leader behaviours would have a stronger positive relationship with leader-focused distributive justice than relational leader behaviours. Contrary to this hypothesis, relational leader behaviours exhibit gen- eral dominance over change leader behaviours (see Table VI, average ΔR2 = .07 > .06). Therefore, Hypothesis 3b was not supported. Hypothesis 4a predicted that task leader behaviours would have a stronger positive re- lationship with organization-focused distributive justice than relational leader behaviours. Contrary to this hypothesis, relational leader behaviours exhibit complete dominance over task leader behaviours (see Table VI, average ΔR2 = .18 > .05). Therefore, Hypothesis 4a was not supported. Hypothesis 4b predicted that change leader behaviours would have a stronger, positive relationship with organization-focused distributive justice than relational leader behaviours. In support of this, we find that change leader behaviours completely dominate relational leader behaviours (i.e., incremental variance explained is greatest for change leader behaviours in all comparison models, see Table VI, average ΔR2 = .19 > .18). Therefore, Hypothesis 4b was supported. Again, worthy of note was that the model R2 for leader-focused distributive justice (.26) was less than for organiza- tion-focused distributive justice (.43). Hypothesis 5 suggested that relational leader behaviours would have a stronger, pos- itive relationship with interpersonal justice than either task (a) or change (b) leader be- haviours. Consistent with this prediction, relational leader behaviours had a stronger positive relationship with interpersonal justice than task leadership behaviours (see Table VII, average ΔR2 = .15 > .11). Therefore, Hypothesis 5a was supported. However, con- trary to this prediction, change leader behaviours generally dominate relational leader behaviours (see Table VII, average ΔR2 = .16 > .15). Therefore, Hypothesis 5b was not supported. Finally, Hypothesis 6 predicted that change leader behaviours would have a stronger positive relationship with informational justice than either task (a) or relational (b) leader behaviours. Incremental variance explained is greatest for change leader behaviours in all comparison models indicating that change leader behaviours completely dominate Illuminating the ‘Face’ of Justice 159 © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies task and relational leader behaviours (see Table VII, average ΔR2 = .29 > .16 and .29 > .17 respectively). Therefore, Hypotheses 6a and 6b were supported. The research questions were concerned with the relative importance of leader be- haviours and justice dimensions in predicting LMX, task performance, and job satis- faction. With regard to research question 1, which assessed the relative importance of leader behaviours and leader-focused justice predictors for LMX, we find that leader behaviours (minimum average ΔR2 = .10) demonstrate general dominance over the justice predictors (maximum average ΔR2 = .09). Further, relational leader behaviours exhibit conditional dominance (Rank = 1 for all subset model sizes) over all other pre- dictors and change leader behaviours exhibit conditional dominance (Rank = 2 for all subset model sizes) over all but relational leader behaviours (model R2 = .72, see Table VIII). Research question 2 investigated the relative importance of leader behaviours and leader- and organization-focused justice predictors on (a) task performance and (b) job satisfaction. For task performance, we find that the general dominance rank order of predictors is task then change leader behaviours followed by informational justice, leader-focused distributive justice, and relational leader behaviours (model R2 = .11, see Table IX). For job satisfaction, we find that the general dominance rank order of predictors is leader-focused distributive justice first, followed by relational, change, and task leader behaviours, followed by organization-focused procedural jus- tice (model R2 = .58, see Table X). Table XI presents a summary of results for all of the hypotheses and research questions. DISCUSSION Research into the impact of effective leader behaviours and organizational justice has demonstrated significant, positive effects on employee affective and behavioural out- comes. However, to date, these studies have not systematically investigated how effective leader behaviours inform justice perceptions, nor has research assessed the joint effects of leadership and justice on social exchange quality and employee outcomes. Therefore, the purpose of this research was twofold. First, we meta-analytically examined the re- lationships between three types of leader behaviours and four dimensions of justice ref- erenced to the leader and the organization. Second, we investigated the joint effects of leader behaviours and justice perceptions to gain a greater understanding of how these assessments of a leader impact LMX, task performance, and job satisfaction. With respect to organizational justice research, our results demonstrate that leader be- haviours differentially inform justice perceptions. Specifically, we found that task leader behaviours were the most important predictor of leader-focused procedural and lead- er-focused distributive justice perceptions. These results provide support for the control theory perspective of procedural justice (Thibaut and Walker, 1975, 1978 ) and the equity theory perspective of distributive justice (Adams, 1965). Conversely, relational leader be- haviours were the most important predictor of organization-focused procedural justice, and change leader behaviours were the most important predictor of organization-fo- cused distributive justice. These results are most consistent with the relational models of procedural justice (Lind and Tyler, 1988) and personal determinants perspective of 160 E. P. Karam et al. © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies T a b le I X . D om in an ce a n al ys is fo r le ad er b eh av io u rs a n d le ad er - an d or ga n iz at io n -f oc u se d ju st ic e pr ed ic ti n g ta sk p er fo rm an ce M od el S iz e Su bs et m od el s C ri te ri on : T as k pe rf or m an ce T as k R el at io na l C ha ng e P J- L dr P J- O rg D J- L dr D J- O rg IJ In fo J Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k k = 0 a ve ra ge (n u ll ) 9 .0 8 1 .0 6 4 .0 7 2 .0 6 5 .0 4 7 .0 5 6 .0 4 7 .0 3 9 .0 7 3 k = 1 a ve ra ge 36 .0 4 1 .0 2 4 .0 3 2 .0 2 6 .0 1 8 .0 2 5 .0 1 7 .0 0 9 .0 2 3 k = 2 a ve ra ge 8 4 .0 2 1 .0 1 5 .0 2 2 .0 1 6 .0 0 8 .0 1 4 .0 0 7 .0 0 9 .0 1 3 k = 3 a ve ra ge 12 6 .0 2 1 .0 1 5 .0 1 2 .0 0 7 .0 0 8 .0 1 3 .0 0 9 .0 0 6 .0 1 4 k = 4 a ve ra ge 12 6 .0 2 1 .0 0 6 .0 1 2 .0 0 8 .0 0 7 .0 1 3 .0 0 9 .0 1 4 .0 1 5 k = 5 a ve ra ge 8 4 .0 1 1 .0 0 7 .0 1 3 .0 0 8 .0 0 6 .0 1 4 .0 0 9 .0 1 2 .0 0 5 k = 6 a ve ra ge 36 .0 1 1 .0 0 7 .0 1 3 .0 0 8 .0 0 6 .0 0 4 .0 0 9 .0 1 2 .0 0 5 k = 7 a ve ra ge 9 .0 1 1 .0 0 7 .0 0 3 .0 0 8 .0 0 4 .0 0 5 .0 0 9 .0 1 2 .0 0 6 k = 8 a ve ra ge 1 .0 1 2 .0 0 8 .0 0 6 .0 0 7 .0 1 3 .0 0 5 .0 0 9 .0 1 1 .0 0 4 O ve ra ll av er ag e .0 2 1 .0 1 5 .0 2 2 .0 1 6 .0 1 8 .0 1 4 .0 1 9 .0 1 7 .0 1 3 M od el R 2 .1 1 N ot es : P J- L d r = le ad er -f oc u se d pr oc ed u ra l j u st ic e; P J- O rg = o rg an iz at io n -f oc u se d pr oc ed u ra l j u st ic e; D J- L d r = le ad er -f oc u se d d is tr ib ut iv e ju st ic e; D J- O rg = o rg an iz at io n -f o - cu se d d is tr ib ut iv e ju st ic e; I J = i n te rp er so n al j u st ic e; I n fo J = i n fo rm at io n al j u st ic e. Δ R 2 = a ve ra ge i n cr em en ta l va ri an ce e xp la in ed b y ad d in g fo ca l va ri ab le a s a pr ed ic to r to su b se t m od el s of s iz e k, w h er e k = n u m b er o f o th er p re d ic to rs i n t h e su b se t m od el . R an k = r an k or d er o f p re d ic to r in t er m s of r el at iv e im p or ta n ce i n p re d ic ti n g cr it er io n ( b as ed on a ve ra ge i n cr em en ta l va ri an ce e xp la in ed , Δ R 2 ) . O ve ra ll av er ag e re pr es en ts t h e av er ag ed a d d it io n al c on tr ib ut io n t o va ri an ce e xp la in ed b y ea ch p re d ic to r ac ro ss a ll su b se t m od el s iz es (i .e ., av er ag e of a ll co n d it io n al v al u es ). Illuminating the ‘Face’ of Justice 161 © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies T a b le X . D om in an ce a n al ys is fo r le ad er b eh av io u rs a n d le ad er - an d or ga n iz at io n -f oc u se d ju st ic e pr ed ic ti n g jo b sa ti sf ac ti on M od el S iz e Su bs et m od el s C ri te ri on : J ob s at is fa ct io n T as k R el at io na l C ha ng e P J- L dr P J- O rg D J- L dr D J- O rg IJ In fo J Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k Δ R 2 R an k k = 0 a ve ra ge (n u ll ) 9 .0 5 9 .2 1 4 .2 3 2 .2 1 4 .2 2 3 .2 8 1 .1 7 7 .1 7 7 .2 1 4 k = 1 a ve ra ge 36 .0 1 9 .0 7 4 .0 8 2 .0 7 5 .0 7 3 .1 4 1 .0 5 7 .0 4 8 .0 6 6 k = 2 a ve ra ge 8 4 .0 2 7 .0 4 3 .0 5 2 .0 4 4 .0 3 5 .1 0 1 .0 2 8 .0 2 9 .0 3 6 k = 3 a ve ra ge 12 6 .0 4 3 .0 3 4 .0 4 2 .0 2 5 .0 1 6 .1 0 1 .0 1 8 .0 1 9 .0 1 7 k = 4 a ve ra ge 12 6 .0 6 2 .0 4 4 .0 4 3 .0 2 5 .0 1 6 .1 0 1 .0 1 8 .0 0 9 .0 1 7 k = 5 a ve ra ge 8 4 .0 8 2 .0 5 3 .0 4 4 .0 2 5 .0 1 6 .1 1 1 .0 1 7 .0 0 9 .0 0 8 k = 6 a ve ra ge 36 .1 1 2 .0 7 3 .0 5 4 .0 2 5 .0 2 6 .1 2 1 .0 1 7 .0 0 8 .0 0 9 k = 7 a ve ra ge 9 .1 4 1 .0 9 3 .0 7 4 .0 3 6 .0 4 5 .1 4 2 .0 1 7 .0 1 8 .0 1 9 k = 8 a ve ra ge 1 .2 0 1 .1 3 3 .1 0 4 .0 4 6 .0 6 5 .1 7 2 .0 1 9 .0 2 8 .0 2 7 O ve ra ll av er ag e .0 8 4 .0 8 2 .0 8 3 .0 5 6 .0 5 5 .1 4 1 .0 3 8 .0 3 9 .0 4 7 M od el R 2 .5 8 N ot es : P J- L d r = le ad er -f oc u se d pr oc ed u ra l j u st ic e; P J- O rg = o rg an iz at io n -f oc u se d pr oc ed u ra l j u st ic e; D J- L d r = le ad er -f oc u se d d is tr ib ut iv e ju st ic e; D J- O rg = o rg an iz at io n -f o - cu se d d is tr ib ut iv e ju st ic e; I J = i n te rp er so n al j u st ic e; I n fo J = i n fo rm at io n al j u st ic e. Δ R 2 = a ve ra ge i n cr em en ta l va ri an ce e xp la in ed b y ad d in g fo ca l va ri ab le a s a pr ed ic to r to su b se t m od el s of s iz e k, w h er e k = n u m b er o f o th er p re d ic to rs i n t h e su b se t m od el . R an k = r an k or d er o f p re d ic to r in t er m s of r el at iv e im p or ta n ce i n p re d ic ti n g cr it er io n ( b as ed on a ve ra ge i n cr em en ta l va ri an ce e xp la in ed , Δ R 2 ) . O ve ra ll av er ag e re pr es en ts t h e av er ag ed a d d it io n al c on tr ib ut io n t o va ri an ce e xp la in ed b y ea ch p re d ic to r ac ro ss a ll su b se t m od el s iz es (i .e ., av er ag e of a ll co n d it io n al v al u es ). 162 E. P. Karam et al. © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies Table XI. Summary of results for hypotheses and research questions Hypothesis/Research Question Result H1(a): Task leader behaviours will exhibit a stronger positive relationship with leader-focused procedural justice perceptions than change leader behaviours. Supported H1(b): Relational leader behaviours will exhibit a stronger positive relation- ship with leader-focused procedural justice perceptions than change leader behaviours. Not supported H2(a): Task leader behaviours will exhibit a stronger positive relationship with organization-focused procedural justice perceptions than change leader behaviours. Not supported H2(b): Relational leader behaviours will exhibit a stronger positive relation- ship with organization-focused procedural justice perceptions than change leader behaviours. Supported H3(a): Task leader behaviours will exhibit a stronger positive relationship with leader-focused distributive justice perceptions than relational leader behaviours. Supported H3(b): Change leader behaviours will exhibit a stronger positive relationship with leader-focused distributive justice perceptions than relational leader behaviours. Not supported H4(a): Task leader behaviours will exhibit a stronger positive relationship with organization-focused distributive justice perceptions than relational leader behaviours. Not supported H4(b): Change leader behaviours will exhibit a stronger positive relationship with organization-focused distributive justice perceptions than relational leader behaviours. Supported H5(a): Relational leader behaviours will exhibit a stronger positive relation- ship with interpersonal justice perceptions than task leader behaviours. Supported H5(b): Relational leader behaviours will exhibit a stronger positive relationship with interpersonal justice perceptions than will change leader behaviours. Not supported H6(a): Change leader behaviours will exhibit a stronger positive relationship with informational justice perceptions than will either task leader behaviours. Supported H6(b): Change leader behaviours will exhibit a stronger positive relationship with informational justice perceptions than will relational leader behaviours. Supported RQ1: When considered simultaneously, what unique contributions do leader behaviours and justice dimensions make to explaining variance in LMX, and what is the relative important of these contributions? Relational leader behaviours exhibit conditional dominance RQ2(a): When considered simultaneously, what unique contributions do leader behaviours and justice dimensions make to explaining variance in task performance, and what is the relative importance of these contributions? Task & change leader behaviours exhibit general dominance RQ2(b): When considered simultaneously, what unique contributions do leader behaviours and justice dimensions make to explaining variance in job satisfaction, and what is the relative importance of these contributions? Leader-focused distribu- tive justice exhibits general dominance Notes: H = hypothesis; RQ = research question. Illuminating the ‘Face’ of Justice 163 © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies distributive justice, which emphasizes the importance of the social and interpersonal aspects of reward allocation decisions (Greenberg, 1993; Levanthal, 1980). Our hypotheses related to interpersonal and informational justice demonstrate sup- port for the role of change leader behaviours in informing these justice dimensions. That is, change leader behaviours that include an emphasis on learning (intellectual stimula- tion), communication, and encouraging employees most inform perceptions of inter- personal and informational justice (Yukl, 2012). However, with regard to interpersonal justice, the overall average variance explained between change and relational behaviours was minimal (.16 vs. .15, respectively), suggesting that both forms of leader behaviours are important to informing interpersonal justice perceptions. Another noteworthy finding of Hypotheses 1–4 was that leader behaviours explain considerably more variance in perceptions of organization-focused procedural and dis- tributive justice than leader-focused procedural and distributive justice. These results provide strong support for the role that leader’s play as an embodiment of the orga- nization (Cropanzano et al., 2001; Eisenberger et al., 2010; Levinson, 1965). Further, these results lend support to the actor-focused model of justice rule adherence proposed by Scott et al. (2009). This model suggests that leaders have various levels of discre- tion in the enactment of justice with the least discretion afforded in distributive justice because of organizational factors (e.g., HR policies or practices) that limit a leader’s decision-making ability. Therefore, whereas effective leader behaviours explained con- siderable variance in all dimensions of justice, they explained the least variance in lead- er-focused distributive justice, which subordinates may attribute to a lack of discretion in outcome allocation decisions. The findings related to our research questions on the unique contributions of leader behaviours and justice dimensions to explaining variance in social exchange quality and employee outcomes are nuanced. With regard to social exchange quality, leader be- haviours dominate the effects. Specifically, relational leader behaviours most inform per- ceptions of LMX followed by change and task leader behaviours. This is consistent with the conceptual definition and empirical evidence for LMX (for a review, see Dulebohn et al., 2012). However, the results also provide some support for the target similarity framework in organizational justice research. That is, of the six target-specific justice dimensions examined in the analysis, three of the four leader-focused justice dimen- sions (interpersonal justice, informational justice, and leader-focused procedural justice), explain, on average, more variance in LMX than the two organization-focused justice dimensions. The results of the research question related to task performance show that task and change leader behaviours were generally the strongest predictors. However, the average variance explained by all leader behaviours and justice dimensions ranged from .01-.02, suggesting that numerous other decisions and behaviours impact task performance. Here again, the results provide support for the target similarity framework given that all four of the leader-focused justice dimensions explained more average variance in task perfor- mance than the two organization-focused justice dimensions. With regard to job satisfaction, leader-focused distributive justice demonstrated con- ditional dominance for all but the very largest models, and all three leader behaviour 164 E. P. Karam et al. © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies categories (i.e., relational, change, and task) demonstrated general dominance over the remaining justice dimensions. This highlights the central role that leader allocation de- cisions and effective leader behaviours play in overall job satisfaction. Given that job satisfaction is generally considered an organization-directed outcome (Rupp et al., 2014), this finding (along with the pattern of average variance explained by the remaining or- ganization- and leader-focused justice dimensions) is counter to target similarity model predictions. However, it reaffirms the powerful role that leaders play in an employee’s experience in the organization (Hui et al., 2004), and it supports the recommendation by Colquitt and colleagues (2013) for scholars to reference all justice dimensions to the leader to better explain variance in outcomes. Theoretical Implications Our results detail several important theoretical contributions. First, we provide evidence that task, relational, and change leader behaviours play a significant role in informing justice perceptions. In fact, the variance explained by leader behaviours in the models examining leader- and organization-focused justice dimensions ranged from .26 to .65, suggesting that employees take into account multiple behaviours of their leader when assessing organizational justice. This shows that research that focuses only on justice decisions likely provides an incomplete assessment of justice perception formation, and future research should incorporate role-relevant leader behaviours into theoretical mod- els of justice perceptions. The differences in findings between the most important predictors of leader-focused procedural and distributive justice perceptions (task leader behaviours) and organiza- tion-focused procedural and distributive justice perceptions (relational and change leader behaviours, respectively) have implications for justice theories as well. Namely, leaders af- fect perceptions of their own procedural and distributive justice through how they carry out concrete and specific activities, likely because of the proximity and salience of these behaviours (Lind et al., 2001). Conversely, it is the more social behaviours (relational and change) that are informative for representing the organization with regard to justice. Change is inevitable in organizations (Van de Ven and Poole, 1995); we show that ef- fective change leaders can positively influence employee perceptions of organization-fo- cused distributive justice. Further, relational leader behaviours – how effective leaders are at showing consideration and respect to employees – influences whether employees perceive the organization as being procedurally fair. The conceptual model presented in this study and the results of the research questions provide evidence of the need for greater integration of leadership and justice theories. These two literatures have evolved largely independently without articulating (a) the be- haviours of a ‘just leader,’ and (b) the impact of a ‘just leader’ on employee outcomes. We demonstrate that ‘just leaders’ impact outcomes differently than what has been reported in prior meta-analyses that have not taken into account a more holistic view of the leader. For example, the organizational justice meta-analysis by Rupp et al. (2014) presented ev- idence that the variance explained in LMX by justice perceptions was .51. In our study, the variance explained in LMX by leader behaviours and justice perceptions is .72: the overall average variance explained by the three leader behaviours is .42, and the overall Illuminating the ‘Face’ of Justice 165 © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies average variance explained by all justice dimensions is .32. This suggests that LMX qual- ity is shaped more by the leader’s behaviours than justice perceptions. As a second ex- ample, the leader behaviour meta-analysis by DeRue et al. (2011) presented data that the variance explained in job satisfaction by task, relational, and change leader behaviours is .51. In our study, when examining the results for job satisfaction, the variance explained by effective leader behaviours is .24 whereas the overall average variance explained by all justice dimensions is .34 (total Model R2 = .58), suggesting that job satisfaction is more influenced by justice perceptions that effective leadership. Therefore, to more accurately assess the effects of leaders in social exchange relationships on employee outcomes, fu- ture research should concurrently consider leader behaviours and justice perceptions. Finally, the high correlations between leader behaviours and justice dimensions (rang- ing from .32 to .75) indicate that employees perceive effective leader behaviours as containing elements of justice. Yet remarkably, there are very few explicit references to justice or fairness in either the theoretical work (e.g., Bass, 1985; Conger and Kanungo, 1987; Fleishman, 1953; Pawar and Eastman, 1997) or the most common measures of effective leader behaviours (e.g., Leader Behavior Description Questionnaire, Stodgill, 1963; Multifactor Leadership Questionnaire, Avolio and Bass, 2004). Therefore, future theoretical and empirical work on effective leader behaviours is needed to clearly artic- ulate and measure the fairness elements of effective task, relational, and change leader behaviours. As a starting point, task leadership research should explicitly articulate the importance of fairness in transactional and contingent reward behaviours such as fairly solving problems and rewarding employee performance equitably. Similarly, relational leadership research should emphasize the fairness aspects of providing support and showing consideration, and change leadership research should emphasize the fair and just communication aspects of a transformational or charismatic leader. Suggestions for Future Research Humphrey (2011) emphasized the importance of advancing the literature through re- views. Therefore, we would like to suggest several opportunities for future research. First, future research on leadership and justice should consider alternate study design and measurement options. Most of the studies in our meta-analysis used the same source of data for measuring leader behaviour and justice variables and/or measured these vari- ables at the same time. Therefore, there could be a ‘halo effect’ affecting the ratings of leadership and justice, and it would be beneficial to disentangle leader behaviours from justice perceptions through measurement that clearly delineates the two. This could be done by examining the collective (i.e., bystander) effects of justice and the contextual factors that may inf luence these perceptions; by separating measurement in time; or by developing multilevel models to explore the effects of executive leadership and justice behaviours on lower level employees. Next, future research should examine moral leader behaviours (e.g., ethical, authentic, moral leadership – see Dinh et al., 2014 for a review) and justice dimensions, and their joint effects on performance outcomes. Given the connection between ethics-related judgments and organizational justice perceptions, these behaviours may have significant implications for justice perceptions. 166 E. P. Karam et al. © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies Also, Rupp and Aguino (2009) have suggested that leadership development pro- grams should include justice as a leadership competency, and we are aware of no research to date to assess these types of programs. The results of our study suggest that leader behaviours and justice dimensions have diverse impacts on outcomes. Therefore, leadership development programs should take into account a broader range of behavioural competencies – including fairness – to have a greater impact on employee outcomes. The primary studies in our sample were largely cross-sectional, so there is a need for future research to examine how perceptions of leadership and justice develop over time. Holtz and Harold (2009) have conducted preliminary research in this area and their re- sults demonstrated that leader-focused justice perceptions do change over time. However, we know little about how leader behaviours inform justice perceptions as the social ex- change relationship develops, stabilizes, and changes. Limitations This study has a number of limitations. First, given that the meta-analyses relied on primary studies as the source of data for analysis, our conclusions are also limited by the limitations in the primary studies. As mentioned above, much of the data measuring leader behaviours and justice dimensions in our study was collected at the same time from the same source. Therefore, the estimated meta-analytic relationships could be inf lated due to common method bias (Podsakoff et al., 2006). In addition, the average number of studies (k) for the correlations between leader behaviours and justice variables is 8.5 (range: 3-23) which is somewhat small relative to the number of independent sam- ples in other leadership and justice meta-analyses. Also, we utilized DA to test the hypotheses because it is a superior statistical method to other types of analyses when assessing the relative importance of correlated predictor variables. However, the interpretation of DA is a qualitative comparison of the relative importance of predictors across model sizes (Budescu, 1993). Therefore, when there are small differences in the average ΔR2 between predictors, the conclusions for these hy- potheses should be interpreted with caution (e.g., Hypothesis 1b found an average ΔR2 of .15 vs. .14 for change and relational leader behaviours, respectively, in predicting leader-focused procedural justice). Furthermore, we were only able to examine a limited number of criterion variables due to the availability of primary data, and consequently we were not able to examine the links between leader behaviours, justice perceptions, and other outcomes such as or- ganizational citizenship behaviours and counterproductive work behaviours. Thus, there is a need and opportunity for scholars to expand research efforts to consider a broader set of employee outcomes. CONCLUSION There has been considerable empirical research into leader behaviours and leader- and organization-focused justice perceptions (Colquitt et al., 2013; DeRue et al., 2011; Rupp Illuminating the ‘Face’ of Justice 167 © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies et al., 2014). However, existing research has yet to assess how effective leader behaviours impact these perceptions of fairness. To address this gap, we meta-analysed the relation- ships between three types of leader behaviours and four dimensions of justice referenced to the leader and the organization in an attempt to provide greater focus on the ‘face’ of organizational justice. Our results demonstrate that task, relational, and change leader behaviours differentially impact perceptions of procedural, distributive, interpersonal, and informational justice. Further, we found that leader behaviours and justice dimen- sions have unique effects on employee outcomes when considered jointly. We hope that future research can utilize these findings as a platform for additional empirical and theoretical advancements in leadership and organizational justice research. ACKNOWLEDGMENT The authors would like to acknowledge and thank Fred Oswald for his helpful guidance on the meta-analytic methods and analyses in the manuscript. We are also grateful to Jim Combs and two anonymous reviewers for their thoughtful comments and efforts toward improving the manuscript. NOTES [1] Our data included one study where interpersonal justice and informational justice were referenced to the organization (i.e., all other studies referenced the leader for these dimensions). This was not surprising given that original theorizing on interpersonal and informational justice suggested these dimensions are social determinants of fairness attributable to a specific source (Greenberg, 1977). Therefore, we do not offer predictions regarding organization-focused interpersonal justice nor orga- nization-focused informational justice. [2] Yukl (2012) actually presents four meta-categories: task, relational, change, and external leadership behaviours. External leadership behaviours include networking, external monitoring, and represent- ing the organization to stakeholders outside of the organization. Given that these behaviours are targeted to non-subordinate employees, they are outside the scope of this study and are not included in our discussion. [3] Supplementary materials with additional coding information, including construct coding definitions and a summary of data included in the meta-analysis (i.e., sample size, correlations, reliabilities, variables, and variable scales) can be found online at the Journal of Management Studies website. [4] Consistent with prior meta-analytic research (Colquitt et al., 2011; Rupp et al., 2009), we coded the following social exchange quality variables noting the target of the exchange quality as well: affec- tive commitment (leader-directed, organization-directed); LMX (leader-directed); perceived support (leader-directed, organization-directed); and trust (leader-directed, organization-directed). In addi- tion, we coded the following affective and behavioural outcome variables noting the target: satisfac- tion (leader-directed); global job satisfaction (organization-directed); identification (leader-directed, organization-directed); counterproductive work behaviours (leader-directed, organization-directed); organizational citizenship behaviours (leader-directed, organization-directed); and task perfor- mance (leader-directed). Given the limited data available from primary studies, only LMX, task performance (leader-directed), and global job satisfaction (organization-directed) were used in the analyses. [5] We are not aware of any published meta-analytic estimates for the correlations among referent-spe- cif ic justice variables. Therefore, in response to a comment from the Associate Editor and an anon- ymous reviewer, we supplemented our original coding by searching the reference section of the 168 E. P. Karam et al. © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies most recent multifoci justice meta-analysis that presents data for the four dimensions of organiza- tional justice (i.e., Colquitt et al., 2011) for studies included in their meta-analysis from the Financial Times 50 journal list. As a result of the search, 84 additional studies (95 independent samples) were coded and added to our dataset. Additional details for this coding are available from the f irst author. REFERENCES Adams, J. S. (1965). ‘Inequity in social exchange’. In Berkowitz, B. (Ed.), Advances in Experimental Social Psycholog y, 2. New York: Academic Press, 267–99. Ambrose, M. L. and Arnaud, A. (2005). ‘Are procedural justice and distributive justice conceptually dis- tinct?’. In Greenberg, J. and Colquitt, J. A. (Eds), Handbook of Organizational Justice. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 59–84. Avolio, B. J. and Bass, B. M. (2004). Multifactor Leadership Questionnaire, 3rd edition. Palo Alto, CA: Mind Garden. Azen, R. and Budescu, D. V. (2003). ‘The dominance analysis approach for comparing predictors in mul- tiple regression’. Psychological Methods, 8, 129–48. Bass, B. M. (1985). Leadership and Performance Beyond Expectations. New York: Free Press. Bass, B. M. (2008). The Bass Handbook of Leadership, 4th edition. New York: Free Press. Bass, B. M. (1990). ‘From transactional to transformational leadership: Learning to share the vision’. Organizational Dynamics, 18, 19–31. Bentler, P. M. and Raykov, T. (2000). ‘On measures of explained variance in nonrecursive structural equation models’. Journal of Applied Psycholog y, 85, 125–31. Blader, S. L. and Tyler, T. R. (2015). ‘Relational models of procedural justice’. In Cropanzano, R. and Ambrose, M. (Eds), The Oxford Handbook of Justice in the Workplace. New York: Oxford University Press, 351–70. Blau, P. M. (1964). Exchange and Power in Social Life. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers. Borman, W. C. and Brush, D. H. (1993). ‘More progress toward a taxonomy of managerial performance requirements’. Human Performance, 6, 1–21. Brower, H. H., Schoorman, F. D. and Tan, H. H. (2000). ‘A model of relational leadership: The integra- tion of trust and leader-member exchange’. The Leadership Quarterly, 11, 227–50. Budescu, D. V. (1993). ‘Dominance analysis: A new approach to the problem of relative importance of predictors in multiple regression’. Psychological Bulletin, 114, 542–51. Burns, J. M. (1978). Leadership. New York: Harper & Row. Cascio, W. F. and Aguinis, H. (2008). ‘Research in industrial and organizational psychology from 1963– 2007: Changes, choices, and trends’. Journal of Applied Psycholog y, 93, 1062–81. Colquitt, J. A. (2001). ‘On the dimensionality of organizational justice: A construct validation of a mea- sure’. Journal of Applied Psycholog y, 86, 386–400. Colquitt, J. A. (2008). ‘Two decades of organizational justice: Findings, controversies, and future direc- tions’. In Cooper, C. L. and Barling, J. (Eds), Sage Handbook of Organizational Behavior. Newbury Park, CA: Sage, 73–88. Colquitt, J. A., Scott, B. A., Rodell, J. B., Long, D. M., Zapata, C. P., Conlon, D. E. and Wesson, M. J. (2013). ‘Justice at the millennium, a decade later: A meta-analytic test of social exchange and af- fect-based perspectives’. Journal of Applied Psycholog y, 98, 199–236. Combs, J. G., Ketchen Jr., D. J., Crook, R. T. and Roth, P. L. (2011). ‘Assessing cumulative evidence within “macro” research: Why meta-analysis should be preferred over vote counting’. Journal of Management Studies, 48, 178–97. Conger, J. A. (1989). ‘Leadership: The art of empowering others’. Academy of Management Executive, 3, 17–24. Conger, J. A. and Kanungo, R. N. (1987). ‘Toward a behavioral theory of charismatic leadership in orga- nizational settings’. Academy of Management Review, 12, 637–47. Cropanzano, R., Byrne, Z. S., Bobocel, D. R. and Rupp, D. E. (2001). ‘Moral virtues, fairness heuristics, social entities, and other denizens of organizational justice’. Journal of Vocational Behavior, 58, 164–209. Cropanzano, R. and Mitchell, M. S. (2005). ‘Social exchange theory: An interdisciplinary review’. Journal of Management, 31, 874–900. Cropanzano, R., Prehar, C. A. and Chen, P. Y. (2002). ‘Using social exchange theory to distinguish pro- cedural from interactional justice’. Group & Organization Management, 27, 324–51. Illuminating the ‘Face’ of Justice 169 © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies De Cremer, D., van Dijke, M. and Bos, A. E. R. (2007). ‘When leaders are seen as transformational: The effects of organizational justice’. Journal of Applied Social Psycholog y, 37, 1797–816. DeRue, D. S., Nahrgang, J. D., Wellman, N. E. D. and Humphrey, S. E. (2011). ‘Trait and behavioral the- ories of leadership: An integration and meta-analytic test of their relative validity’. Personnel Psycholog y, 64, 7–52. Dierdorff, E. C., Rubin, R. S. and Morgeson, F. P. (2009). ‘The milieu of managerial work: an integrative framework linking work context to role requirements’. Journal of Applied Psycholog y, 94, 972–88. Dinh, J. E., Lord, R. G., Gardner, W. L., Meuser, J. D., Liden, R. C. and Hu, J. (2014). ‘Leadership the- ory and research in the new millennium: Current theoretical trends and changing perspectives’. The Leadership Quarterly, 25, 36–62. Duval, S. and Tweedie, R. (2000). ‘A nonparametric “Trim and Fill” method of accounting for publication bias in meta-analysis’. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 95, 89–98. Dulebohn, J. H., Bommer, W. H., Liden, R. C., Brouer, R. L. and Ferris, G. R. (2012). ‘A meta-analysis of antecedents and consequences of leader-member exchange: Integrating the past with an eye toward the future’. Journal of Management, 38, 1715–59. Eisenberger, R., Karagonlar, G., Stinglhamber, F., Neves, P., Becker, T. E., Gonzalez-Morales, M. G. and Steiger-Mueller, M. (2010). ‘Leader–member exchange and affective organizational commit- ment: The contribution of supervisor’s organizational embodiment’. Journal of Applied Psycholog y, 95, 1085–103. Eisenberger, R., Stinglhamber, F., Vandenberghe, C., Sucharski, I. L. and Rhoades, L. (2002). ‘Perceived supervisor support: contributions to perceived organizational support and employee retention’. Journal of Applied Psycholog y, 87, 565–73. Fleishman, E. A. (1953). ‘The description of supervisory behavior’. Journal of Applied Psycholog y, 37, 1–6. Frazier, M. L., Johnson, P. D., Gavin, M., Gooty, J. and Snow, D. B. (2010). ‘Organizational justice, trust- worthiness, and trust: A multifoci examination’. Group & Organization Management, 35, 39–76. Gardner, W. L., Lowe, K. B., Moss, T. W., Mahoney, K. T. and Cogliser, C. C. (2010). ‘Scholarly leader- ship of the study of leadership: A review of The Leadership Quarterly’s second decade, 2000–2009’. The Leadership Quarterly, 21, 922–58. Gottfredson, R. K. and Aguinis, H. (2016). ‘Leadership behaviors and follower performance: Deductive and inductive examination of theoretical rationales and underlying mechanisms’. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 38, 558–91. Gouldner, A. W. (1960). ‘The norm of reciprocity: A preliminary statement’. American Sociological Review, 25, 161–78. Graen, G. B. and Scandura, T. A. (1987). ‘Toward a psychology of dyadic organizing’. Research in Organizational Behavior, 9, 175–208. Greenberg, J. (1993). ‘The social side of fairness: Interpersonal and informational classes of organiza- tional justice’. In Cropanzano, R. (Ed.), Justice in the Workplace: Approaching Fairness in Human Resource Management. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 79–103. Greenleaf, R. K. (1977). Servant Leadership: A Journey into the Nature of Legitimate Power and Greatness. New York: Paulist Press. Holtz, B. C. and Harold, C. M. (2009). ‘Fair today, fair tomorrow? A longitudinal investigation of overall justice perceptions’. Journal of Applied Psycholog y, 94, 1185–99. Holtz, B. C. and Harold, C. M. (2013). ‘Effects of leadership consideration and structure on employee perceptions of justice and counterproductive work behavior’. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 34, 492–519. Howell, J. M. and Avolio, B. J. (1993). ‘Transformational leadership, transactional leadership, locus of control, and support for innovation: Key predictors of consolidated-business-unit performance’. Journal of Applied Psycholog y, 78, 891–902. Hui, C., Lee, C. and Rousseau, D. M. (2004). ‘Employment relationships in China: Do workers related to the organization or to people’. Organization Science, 15, 232–40. Hulin, C. L. and Judge, T. A. (2003). ‘Job attitudes’. In Borman, W. C., Ilgen, D. R. and Klimoski, R. J. (Eds), Handbook of Psycholog y: Industrial and Organizational Psycholog y. Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley & Sons, 255–76. Humphrey, S. E. (2011). ‘What does a great meta-analysis look like?’. Organizational Psycholog y Review, 1, 99–103. Hunter, J. E. and Schmidt, F. L. (2004). Methods of Meta-analysis: Correcting Error and Bias in Research Findings, 2nd edition. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. 170 E. P. Karam et al. © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies Johnson, J. W. (2000). ‘A heuristic method for estimating the relative weight of predictor variables in mul- tiple regression’. Multivariate Behavioral Research, 35, 1–19. Judge, T. A., Piccolo, R. E. and Ilies, R. (2004). ‘The forgotten ones? The validity of consideration and initiating structure in leadership research’. Journal of Applied Psycholog y, 89, 36–51. Judge, T. A., Thoresen, C. J., Bono, J. E. and Patton, G. K. (2001). ‘The job satisfaction-job performance relationship: A qualitative and quantitative review’. Psychological Bulletin, 127, 376–407. Kahai, S. S., Sosik, J. J. and Avolio, B. J. (1997). ‘Effects of leadership style and problem structure on work group process and outcomes in an electronic meeting system environment’. Personnel Psycholog y, 50, 121–46. Kepes, S., McDaniel, M. A., Brannick, M. T. and Banks, G. C. (2013). ‘Meta-analytic reviews in the orga- nizational sciences: Two meta-analytic schools on the way to MARS (the Meta-Analytic Reporting Standards)’. Journal of Business and Psycholog y, 28, 123–43. Kirkman, B. L., Chen, G., Farh, J.-L., Chen, Z. X. and Lowe, K. B. (2009). ‘Individual power distance orientation and follower reactions to transformational leaders: A cross-level, cross-cultural examina- tion’. Academy of Management Journal, 52, 744–64. Lavelle, J. J., McMahan, G. C. and Harris, C. M. (2009). ‘Fairness in human resource management, so- cial exchange relationships, and citizenship behavior: Testing linkages of the target similarity model among nurses in the United States’. International Journal of Human Resource Management, 20, 2419–34. Lavelle, J. J., Rupp, D. E. and Brockner, J. (2007). ‘Taking a multifoci approach to the study of justice, social exchange, and citizenship behavior: The target similarity model’. Journal of Management, 33, 841–66. Levanthal, G. S. (1980). ‘What should be done with equity theory? New approaches to the study of fairness in social relationships’. In Gergen, K. J., Greenberg, M. S. and Willis, R. H. (Eds), Social Exchange: Advances in Theory and Research. New York: Plenum Press, 27–55. Levinson, H. (1965). ‘Reciprocation: The relationship between man and organization’. Administrative Science Quarterly, 9, 370–90. Liao, H. and Rupp, D. E. (2005). ‘The impact of justice climate and justice orientation on work outcomes: A cross-level multifoci framework’. Journal of Applied Psycholog y, 90, 242–56. Liden, R. C. and Maslyn, J. M. (1998). ‘Multidimensionality of leader-member exchange: An empirical assessment through scale development’. Journal of Management, 24, 43–72. Lind, E. A. (2001). ‘Fairness heuristic theory: Justice judgments as pivotal cognitions in organizational relations’. In Greenberg, J. (Ed.), Advances in Organizational Justice. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 56–88. Lind, E. A., Kanfer, R. and Earley, P. C. (1990). ‘Voice, control, and procedural justice: Instrumental and noninstrumental concerns in fairness judgments’. Journal of Personality and Social Psycholog y, 59, 952–59. Lind, E. A., Kray, L. and Thompson, L. (2001). ‘Primacy effects in justice judgments: Testing predictions from fairness heuristic theory’. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 85, 189–210. Lind, E. A. and Tyler, T. R. (1988). The Social Psycholog y of Procedural Justice. New York: Plenum Press. Masterson, S. S. and Lensges, M. (2015). ‘Leader–member exchange and justice’. In Bauer, T. N. and Erdogan, B. (Eds), The Oxford Handbook of Leader-Member Exchange. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 67–84. Martin, R., Guillaume, Y., Thomas, G., Lee, A. and Epitropaki, O. (2016). ‘Leader-member exchange (LMX) and performance: A meta-analytic review’. Personnel Psycholog y, 69, 67–121. Mintzberg, H. (1973). The Nature of Managerial Work. New York: Harper & Row. Mitchell, M. S., Cropanzano, R. S. and Quisenberry, D. M. (2012). ‘Social exchange theory, exchange re- sources, and interpersonal relationships: A modest resolution of theoretical difficulties’. In Tornblom, K. and Kazemi, A. (Eds), Handbook of Social Resource Theory. New York: Springer, 99–118. Ng, T. W. (2017). ‘Transformational leadership and performance outcomes: Analyses of multiple media- tion pathways’. The Leadership Quarterly, 28, 385–417. Nimon, K. and Oswald, F. L. (2013). ‘Understanding the results of multiple linear regression: Beyond standardized regression coefficients’. Organizational Research Methods, 16, 650–74. Pawar, B. S. and Eastman, K. K. (1997). ‘The nature and implications of contextual inf luences on trans- formational leadership: A conceptual review’. Academy of Management Review, 22, 80–109. Podsakoff, P. M., Bommer, W. H., Podsakoff, N. P. and MacKenzie, S. B. (2006). ‘Relationships between leader reward and punishment behavior and subordinate attitudes, perceptions, and behaviors: A meta-analytic review of existing and new research’. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 99, 113–42. Illuminating the ‘Face’ of Justice 171 © 2018 John Wiley & Sons Ltd and Society for the Advancement of Management Studies Rotundo, M. and Sackett, P. R. (2002). ‘The relative importance of task, citizenship, and counterproduc- tive performance to global ratings of job performance: A policy-capturing approach’. Journal of Applied Psycholog y, 87, 66–80. Rupp, D. E. and Aquino, K. F. (2009). ‘Nothing so practical as a good justice theory’. Industrial and Organizational Psycholog y, 2, 205–10. Rupp, D. E. and Cropanzano, R. (2002). ‘The mediating effects of social exchange relationships in pre- dicting workplace outcomes from multifoci organizational justice’. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 89, 925–46. Rupp, D. E., Shao, R., Jones, K. S. and Liao, H. (2014). ‘The utility of a multifoci approach to the study of organizational justice: A meta-analytic investigation into the consideration of normative rules, moral accountability, bandwidth-fidelity, and social exchange’. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 123, 159–85. Scott, B. A., Colquitt, J. A. and Paddock, E. L. (2009). ‘An actor-focused model of justice rule adherence and violation: The role of managerial motives and discretion’. Journal of Applied Psycholog y, 94, 756–69. Spreitzer, G. (2007). ‘Giving peace a chance: Organizational leadership, empowerment, and peace’. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 28, 1077–95. Steichen, T. J. (2000). ‘Updates of tests for publication bias in meta-analysis’. Stata Technical Bulletin, 57, 4. Stinglhamber, F., Marique, G., Caesens, G., Hanin, D. and De Zanet, F. (2015). ‘The inf luence of trans- formational leadership on followers’ affective commitment: The role of perceived organizational support and supervisor’s organizational embodiment’. Career Development International, 20, 583–603. Stodgill, R. M. (1963). Manual for the Leader Behavior Description Questionnaire – Form XII. Columbus, OH: Ohio State University, Bureau of Business Research. Tett, R. P., Guterman, H. A., Bleier, A. and Murphy, P. J. (2000). ‘Development and content validation of a “hyperdimensional” taxonomy of managerial competence’. Human Performance, 13, 205–51. Thibaut, J. and Walker, L. (1975). Procedural Justice: A Psychological Analysis. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Thibaut, J. and Walker, L. (1978). ‘A theory of procedure’. California Law Review, 66, 541–66. Tyler, T. R. (1989). ‘The psychology of procedural justice: A test of the group-value model’. Journal of Personality and Social Psycholog y, 57, 830–38. Tyler, T. R. and Blader, S. L. (2000). Cooperation in Groups: Procedural Justice, Social Identity, and Behavioral Engagement. New York: Psychology Press. Tyler, T. R. and Lind, E. A. (1992). ‘A relational model of authority in groups’. Advances in Experimental Social Psycholog y, 25, 115–91. Van de Ven, A. H. and Poole, M. S. (1995). ‘Explaining development and change in organizations’. Academy of Management Review, 20, 510–40. Wayne, S. J., Shore, L. M., Bommer, W. H. and Tetrick, L. E. (2002). ‘The role of fair treatment and rewards in perceptions of organizational support and leader-member exchange’. Journal of Applied Psycholog y, 87, 590–98. Wofford, J. C. and Liska, L. Z. (1993). ‘Path-goal theories of leadership: A meta-analysis’. Journal of Management, 19, 857–876. Yukl, G. (2012). ‘Effective leadership behavior: What we know and what questions need more attention’. Academy of Management Perspectives, 26, 66–85. Yukl, G., Gordon, A. and Taber, T. (2002). ‘A hierarchical taxonomy of leadership behavior: Integrating a half century of behavior research’. Journal of Leadership & Organizational Studies, 9, 15–32. Zhang, Y., LePine, J. A., Buckman, B. R. and Wei, F. (2014). ‘It’s not fair… or is it? The role of justice and leadership in explaining work stressor–job performance relationships’. Academy of Management Journal, 57, 675–97. S U P P O R T I N G I N F O R M A T I O N Additional supporting information may be found online in the Supporting Information section at the end of the article. work_echuputsiffsdffptirhn7ayd4 ---- Humane Forensic Practice Serves Social Justice Humane Forensic Practice Serves Social Justice Anna R. Weissman, MD, and Philip J. Candilis, MD In response to a call for revision of the current procedures for involuntary treatment in Massachusetts, this commentary explores the ethics basis for such institutional reform. In the decades since the landmark Rogers v. Commissioner decision of 1983, the ethics foundation for forensic psychiatry has evolved from a purist approach that prioritized legal values above therapeutic ones. Building on systemic approaches by Gutheil et al. and Ciccone and Clements, Candilis and Martinez, for example, have argued that a robust professional ethic requires moving beyond the strict role theory of the adversarial system to consider broader approaches that integrate multiple perspec- tives: the ultimate goal is protection of vulnerable people and ideas. In this commentary, we suggest that the current system for involuntary treatment does not protect the vulnerable people it ought to serve, failing the neglected goal of social justice. J Am Acad Psychiatry Law 46:454 –57, 2018. DOI:10.29158/JAAPL.003796-18 This important piece by Biswas et al.1 examines the unintended consequences of the process for involun- tary treatment in Massachusetts following the 1983 Rogers v Commissioner decision by the Massachusetts Supreme Judicial Court.2 The authors make a strong case that the delays in treatment inherent in the cur- rent adversarial system result in mental deterioration that deprives patients of liberation from symptoms and leads to a more severe course of illness. The au- thors describe the current process as a consequence of “the steady development of a mental health jurispru- dence dedicated to the preservation of human rights,”1 acknowledging that self-determination and autonomy are critical aspects of this perspective (Ref. 1, p 447). While we agree that autonomy is an important ethics principle, it is only one aspect of human rights. Empowering patients to make in- formed decisions about their treatment is central to the practice of medicine and law; but the key word is “informed.” When a person is unable to make an informed decision about treatment due to mental illness, the unwavering pursuit of autonomy be- comes a distortion of human rights. The U.S. legal system addresses conflicting values by pitting them against one another. Similarly, the current system of mental health jurisprudence is a battlefield where individual good vies with social good and medical values clash with legal ones. These polarized constructs can lead to tunnel vision, obfus- cating rather than elucidating the complex human condition. In contrast, the human mind traffics in ambivalence. From molecules to cells to circuits, the brain is engaged in a constant, active, and sophisti- cated balancing act; not “either/or,” but “both/and.” At the intersection of medicine and the law, forensic psychiatry is ideally positioned to navigate conflict- ing values and uncover complex truths. The ethics foundation of forensic psychiatry has evolved in recent decades to embrace a homeostatic balance between conflicting principles.3 In their the- ory of decision analysis, Gutheil and colleagues4 pointed out the complexity of interactions between individuals, their institutions, and society at large. They suggested a decision-making system that bal- ances the tension of values, tension between profes- sions, and tension between objective and subjective factors. They eschewed a purist view of strict roles and argued for a collaborative network that addresses the moral claims of the individual, clinician, and so- ciety all at once. Ciccone and Clements5 also em- braced this synthesis in their systems approach to Dr. Weissman is Associate Director, Psychiatry Residency Training Pro- gram, Assistant Professor of Psychiatry and Behavioral Sciences, George Washington University School of Medicine, Washington, DC. Dr. Can- dilis is Interim Director of Medical Affairs, Saint Elizabeths Hospital, and Professor of Psychiatry and Behavioral Sciences, George Washington Uni- versity School of Medicine, Washington, DC. Address correspondence to: Anna R. Weissman, MD, Department of Psychiatry & Behavioral Sci- ences, George Washington University School of Medicine and Health Sciences, 2120 L Street, NW, Suite 600, Washington, DC 20037. E-mail: anna.weissman@gmail.com Disclosures of financial or other potential conflicts of interest: None. 454 The Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law C O M M E N T A R Y forensic psychiatry. They suggested an ethics model that reflects “the inevitable conflict between two dif- ferent levels of good and suggests homeostatic mech- anisms for dealing with such conflicts” (Ref. 5, p 265). Their dialectical approach offers a broader, more nuanced perspective on the problem of invol- untary treatment: “Respect for individuals is a more useful concept than rights and autonomy concepts in the development of a medical ethic . . . we must re- define respect for individuals to include empathy and concern for the individual’s best interest, rather than only respect for reason” (Ref. 5, p 275). As Biswas et al.1 point out, there is an inherent paradox in for- going a best-interest model for substituted judgment when incompetency stems from treatable mental ill- ness; if the person were competent, he would not need involuntary treatment. Beyond balancing conflicting principles, the eth- ics practice of forensic psychiatry requires attention to the stories of marginalized individuals. In his nar- rative approach to forensic ethics, Ezra Griffith called for a cultural formulation, contending that there could be no justice in ethics frameworks that ignore the different treatment of dominant and nondomi- nant groups.6 Matthew Wynia and colleagues7 sim- ilarly pointed to the importance of advocating for the disenfranchised in their 1999 article in the New Eng- land Journal of Medicine, arguing that “professions protect not only vulnerable persons but also vulner- able social values” (Ref. 7, p 1612). Candilis and Martinez8 built on these ideas in their unifying ethics theory of robust professionalism, integrating the complex personal, social, and institutional commit- ments of forensic work. They described the forensic encounter as a moral relationship and proposed us- ing an individual’s narrative to enrich the way that principles are applied to specific cases. Biswas et al.1 echo the call for a more nuanced approach to indi- viduals and their stories: “A single law [to determine capacity for those with mental illness] cannot address the entire problem . . . it is a blunt instrument” (Ref. 1, p 450). More recently, Alec Buchanan9 connected the principle of respect for persons with a respect for human dignity. He suggests correctly that “the link between dignity and vulnerability may be that we see people as needing a minimum level of wellbeing and freedom to act in pursuit of their goals” (Ref. 9, p 15). Buchanan specifically points to the importance of dignity in issues of competence: “Respecting dig- nity when people are not competent to make their own choices seems to require us to do things other than simply respect their decisions. It seems to in- clude, for instance, acting to ensure that their best interests are protected” (Ref. 9, p 13). Buchanan’s call echoes that of Ciccone and Clements decades earlier. When individuals with mental illness are commit- ted without treatment, there are two frequent out- comes. The first scenario is well characterized by Bis- was et al.1; they languish in a medical institution, “rotting with their rights on”10 or receiving treat- ment on an inconsistent, emergency basis that is traumatic and ineffective. Another common scenario is that they are discharged, despite remaining actively in crisis, and subsequently arrested for a (usually) minor criminal offense. These encounters with law enforcement can be deadly; up to 25 percent of fatal police shootings in the United States in 2015 and 2016 involved individuals who had mental illness.11 To appreciate the regularity of this diversion to the criminal justice system, one need only look as far as our jails and prisons, where the rate of serious mental illness far exceeds the rate in the general population.12,13 The failure to treat involuntarily hospitalized in- dividuals contributes to the disproportionate arrest and incarceration of the most vulnerable people in our society. People of color with mental illness are overrepresented in prisons.14 –16 This is a result of systemic racial bias; but racism is not the only mar- ginalizing force at work in the incarceration of people with mental illness. Incarcerated individuals are not only people of color who are disproportionately af- fected by serious mentally illness, they are also far more likely than the general population to be low-income, under-employed, under-housed, and under-educated.17 These intersecting, multiply-mar- ginalized identities lead to exponential stigmatiza- tion and disempowerment.18 Even when they are once again involuntarily insti- tutionalized this time in jail many of these vulnerable individuals will continue to be deprived of treatment for weeks to months until their attorneys finally ar- gue that they are incompetent: not to refuse treat- ment, but to stand trial. This well-known back door to treatment comes at an astronomically high cost, not just for the state, but for these most marginalized citizens who endure the repeated trauma of commit- ment, arrest, detention, and incarceration. Weissman and Candilis 455Volume 46, Number 4, 2018 When they finally receive treatment, most will be restored to competence and go on to stand trial.19 Whether justice is ultimately served in these cases is another matter. Many will be incarcerated for acts that they had no capacity to understand or control. Despite the lack of mens rea, they will not pursue an insanity defense because, in many jurisdictions, suc- cess would lead to longer confinement. Others, hav- ing experienced the deleterious effects of extended, untreated mental illness, will be found not compe- tent and not restorable. According to the landmark Jackson v. Indiana20 decision, they are subject to civil commitment proceedings. Those who are ultimately found not competent, not restorable, and not com- mittable will have their charges dropped. They will be swiftly discharged, often with little planning, no housing, and no leverage to continue outpatient treatment. While only a minority of defendants fall into this category, those who do are vastly overrepre- sented in the criminal justice system and in forensic psychiatric settings. With no justice and no treat- ment, the cycle of illness, arrest, and trauma is free to accelerate: the brakes are cut. Social justice is integral to the ethics mission of many professions; in medicine, it requires promoting the fair distribution of health care resources and working actively to eliminate discrimination in health care.21 In forensic psychiatry, ethics ap- proaches have evolved to integrate social context, multiple perspectives, and the narratives of vulnera- ble individuals. These more nuanced approaches all indicate that respect for individuals encompasses far more than just autonomy. But current adversarial procedures for involuntary treatment prioritize au- tonomy above all else, not just at the expense of hu- man dignity, but at the expense of social justice. There can be no justice of any kind when the most vulnerable citizens are deprived of appropriate health care and left to languish in medical, forensic, and correctional institutions. The gross discrepancies in life expectancy for persons with mental illness that may, as Biswas et al. suggest, result in part from treatment non-adherence, represent another social injustice.1 The goals of psychiatry and the law are often not the same; but a set of procedures that pits one against the other is no longer a solution. As Ciccone and Clements5 pointed out in the early days of Rogers, “Working in a setting that calls for a balanced tension can be disturbing to those who want a neat ethical system with ideal resolutions to problems, but this does not express the human social condition . . .” (Ref. 5, p 273). Across professions, judges, attorneys, and physicians take different approaches to achieve the common goal of protecting vulnerable people, but there may already be more common ground than the current procedures acknowledge. Attorneys and judges find themselves in a situa- tion similar to physicians when they recognize that a vulnerable person in their care needs treatment. As Schouten and Gutheil22 pointed out in their empir- ical assessment of the costs of the Rogers decision, the vast majority of petitions pursued to completion (99.1%) were granted by the courts. They hypothe- sized that “despite requirement for substituted judg- ment analysis, judges may exhibit some bias toward the more humanitarian (but less libertarian) tradi- tional best-interest analysis” (Ref. 22, p 1350). Sim- ilarly, they suggested that “some attorneys might yield to their own interpretation of fiduciary respon- sibility and present a pro forma or less-than-aggressive opposing argument” (Ref. 22, p 1350). Forensic psy- chiatry is not the only profession that benefits from an integrated ethics approach that protects vulnera- ble people. While the prospect of reform may be daunting, Elizabeth Wolgast23 reminds us why we must move forward: “The motive for tackling these gargantuan projects of reform is that the alternative is a further thinning in the meaning of responsibility on one side while nurturing institutions that defeat it on the other. A decision to change is acutely a moral deci- sion, and moral courage is needed to make it” (Ref. 23, p 157). Some forensic authors have already sug- gested that the strict, strong, or narrow professional role may well be the concept that allows for what Wolgast described as the “further thinning of indi- vidual responsibility” (Ref. 23, p 157). It is the broader view of professional role that allows redress of social inequities and their visitation on vulnerable persons. More recent commentators24 contend that “we will have to look carefully at the connection between professional role and institutional or societal needs if we are to develop the ‘moral courage’ to seek reform” (Ref. 24, p 109). The moral courage to re- form is at the core of social justice. References 1. Biswas J, Drogin EY, Gutheil TG: Is treatment delayed is treat- ment denied. J Am Acad Psychiatry Law 46:447– 453, 2018 Humane Forensic Practice Serves Social Justice 456 The Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law 2. Rogers v. Commissioner of the Department of Mental Health, 390 Mass. 489 (1983) 3. Griffith EEH (Editor): Ethics Challenges in Forensic Psychiatry and Psychology Practice. New York: Columbia University Press, 2018 4. Gutheil TG, Burstajn HJ, Brodsky A, et al: Decision Making in Psychiatry and the Law. Baltimore, MD: Williams & Wilkins, 1991 5. Ciccone JR, Clements CD: The ethical practice of forensic psy- chiatry: a view from the trenches. Bull Am Acad Psychiatry Law 23:263–77, 1994 6. Griffith EEH: Ethics in forensic psychiatry: a cultural response to Stone and Appelbaum. J Am Acad Psychiatry Law 26:171– 84, 1998 7. Wynia MK, Lathan SR, Kao AC, et al: Medical professionalism in society. N Engl J Med 341:1612– 6, 1999 8. Candilis PJ, Martinez R, Dording C: Principles and narrative in forensic psychiatry: toward a robust view of professional role. J Am Acad Psychiatry Law 29:167–73, 2001 9. Buchanan A: Respect for dignity and forensic psychiatry. Int’l J L & Psychiatry 41:12–17, 2015 10. Applebaum PS, Gutheil TG: “Rotting with their rights on”: con- stitutional theory and clinical reality in drug refusal by psychiatric patients. Bull Am Acad Psychiatry Law 7:308 –17, 1979 11. Frankham E: Mental illness affects police fatal shootings. Con- texts 17:70 –72, 2018 12. Steadman HJ, Osher FC, Robbins PC, et al: Prevalence of serious mental illness among jail inmates. Psychiatr Serv 60:761–5, 2009 13. James DJ, Glaze LE: Mental health problems of prison and jail inmates. Special Report, Bureau of Justice Statistics, 2006 14. Grekin PM, Jemelka R, Trupin EW: Racial differences in the criminalization of the mentally ill. Bull Am Acad Psychiatry Law 22:411–20, 1994 15. Hawthorne WB, Folsom DP, Sommerfeld DH, et al: Incarcera- tion among adults who are in the public mental health system: rates, risk factors, and short-term outcomes. Psychiatr Serv 63: 26 –32, 2012 16. Fisher WH, Roy-Bujnowski KM, Grudzinskas AJ Jr, et al: Pat- terns and prevalence of arrest in a statewide cohort of mental health care consumers. Psychiatr Serv 57:1623–28, 2006 17. Greenberg G, Rosenheck R: Jail incarceration, homelessness, and mental health: a national study. Psychiatr Serv 59:170 –7, 2008 18. Crenshaw K: Demarginalizing the intersection of race and sex: a black feminist critique of antidiscrimination doctrine, feminist theory and antiracist policies. U Chi Legal F 1:139 – 67, 1989 19. Mossman D: Predicting restorability of incompetent criminal de- fendants. J Am Acad Psychiatry Law 35:34 – 43, 2007 20. Jackson v. Indiana, 406 U.S. 715 (1972) 21. ABIM Foundation, ACP-ASIM Foundation, European Federa- tion of Internal Medicine: Medical professionalism in the new millennium: a physician charter. Ann Intern Med 136:243– 6, 2002 22. Schouten R, Gutheil TG: Aftermath of the Rogers decision: assess- ing the costs. Am J Psychiatry 147:1348 –52, 1990 23. Wolgast E: Ethics of an Artificial Person. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press, 1992 24. Candilis PJ, Weinstock R, Martinez R: Forensic Ethics and the Expert Witness. New York: Springer Publishing Co., 2007 Weissman and Candilis 457Volume 46, Number 4, 2018 work_edpcmuqvrzglng2u7fluk6riku ---- Microsoft Word - 00 Prelims 15(1).doc LAWYERS, JUSTICE AND THE STATE The Sliding Signifier of Law in Popular Culture Jason Bainbridge* This article examines how the concept of ‘law’ is culturally defined through a semiotic analysis of some of the ways in which law is constructed in popular culture. The article goes on to map the changing signifier of law across a number of film and television series, from the heroic lawyer to the embodiment of the ‘state’, the police officer and the government agent. In each case, analysis is provided of how the change in signifier alters the corresponding signified of ‘law’ — and the implications this change has for the pursuit of justice and fidelity to the rule of law. It is suggested that the popular cultural signifier of law has slid further and further away from the modern rule of law towards an increasingly transcendent and interventionist pursuit of justice, pushing the boundaries and promoting debate over what law can and should be. The policeman’s job is only easy in a police state. That’s the whole point, captain. Who is the boss, the cop or the law? — ‘Mike’ Vargas (Charlton Heston), Touch of Evil You’re only Spider-Man Dad, not God. —Charlie Deed (to her father, Judge John Deed), Everyone’s Child Introduction The term ‘law’ has many possible meanings, not just in legal institutions (where it can refer to positivist law, natural law, Indigenous law or police powers) but also in the wider culture. Law, it seems, is a malleable concept, its definition often depending upon the context in which it is found. Despite this, legal and cultural theorist Steve Redhead notes that conventionally ‘in jurisprudential and political theory’, law is taken as a given — ‘we assume that we know what it is and where to find it, and also what it does’.1 Redhead goes * School of Journalism, Media & Communications, University of Tasmania 1 Redhead (1995), p 10. Interestingly, this does not seem to be the case in practice. The adversary system is, in part, based on the idea that law can be interpreted differently. Similarly the composition of courts acknowledge that judges interpret 154 GRIFFITH LAW REVIEW (2006) VOL 15 NO 1 on to suggest that this is in fact ‘a powerful (legal) fiction which may be crucial to the exercise of political power and legal authority across many different fields, especially the “cultural”’.2 One possible starting point for understanding how law is culturally defined is through Swiss linguist Ferdinand de Saussure’s notion of semiotics,3 the study of communication. Adopting a structuralist approach to communication, de Saussure breaks down communication practices into a series of units called signs. A sign is anything that produces a meaning. Each sign is comprised of a physical component (the signifier) and a mental concept associated with that physical component (the signified). The relationship between the signifier and the signified is called signification, the process by which meaning is made.4 Thus, when we are confronted with a statue of justice, an image of a courtroom, or the figure of a lawyer or a policeman, we can understand them all as the physical signifiers of the mental signified — law. Saussurean semiotics is therefore useful because it provides a set of tools to describe how law is culturally constructed. It permits an analysis of culture without the imposition of value judgments (based on artistic or moral merit) and, unlike empirical sociology, can focus on individual texts rather than large- scale patterns.5 Furthermore, despite criticisms that it is too abstract and formalist in its approach, semiotics is committed to the social production of meaning. For Saussure, meaning is not contained in a single sign, but rather exists in the various sorts of relationships into which a sign enters.6 Of particular importance here would be the relationship between law and justice. Saussure therefore seems to be acknowledging that meaning is contextual. This is incredibly important in the analysis of law because, as noted above, the very meaning of law seems to depend on the context in which it is found. Therefore, as the physical signifier of law changes, so too does the mental concept of law that is signified. This article adopts a semiotic analysis of some of the ways in which law is constructed in popular culture. The article maps the changing signifier of law in popular culture from the heroic lawyer to the embodiment of the ‘state’, the police and the government agent. In each case, analysis is provided of how the change in signifier alters the corresponding signified of ‘law’ — and of the implications this change has for the pursuit of justice and fidelity to the rule of law. The examples are all drawn from film and television because, as Meyrowitz notes, film and television are the most prevalent popular cultural laws differently; some believe the constitution, for example, to be a living document while others turn to what the original drafters of the law intended. 2 Redhead (1995), p 10. 3 de Saussure (1983 [1916]). 4 De Saussure (1983); Hawkes (1977). 5 Fiske (1982); O’Sullivan et al (1994). 6 Culler (1976). BAINBRIDGE: LAWYERS, JUSTICE AND THE STATE 155 forms and therefore the most accessible to a mass audience.7 As Roland Barthes notes, ‘iconic images [be it Perry Mason or Harry Callaghan] distil complex details [of legal process] into blissful clarity’.8 This makes film and television ‘the main source of common knowledge about the law … [exerting] a powerful influence on ordinary people’s attitudes to, and expectations of, law and the legal system’9 because they are so much more accessible to the general public than law reports or even visiting courtrooms for themselves. Beyond simply representing the legal system, we can also read film and television as being in a dialogic relationship with these ideas, actively commenting upon these notions of law and justice. Cultural theorist Douglas Rushkoff,10 for example, has suggested that ‘popular cultural forums’ (like film and television) offer a ‘conceptual interface between the order of our laws and the chaos of our world’11 that makes them ‘the place for us to evaluate our rules and customs’.12 Film and television are therefore vitally important for making visible how law is constructed and, in the very process of representing law on screen, putting these ideas into the public sphere where they can be debated and contested.13 Following Bennett and Woollacott’s study,14 the examples are wide- ranging (from America, England and Australia) and there is some deliberate slippage between film and television. It is submitted that any other approach would be too limiting, abstracting texts from the wider culture and ‘the shifting orders of inter-textuality’15 which both elucidate their meaning and demonstrate how widespread these ideas of law truly are. Focusing on lawyers, policemen and government agents, this article aims to trace ways of thinking about law across related areas of popular culture by following ideas through intertexts with common concerns. The article then concludes with a consideration of why these ideas are important and what they can tell us about the changing nature of ‘legal authority’16 in the wider culture. 7 Meyrowitz (1985). 8 Barthes (1972), p 143. 9 Laster (2000), pp 10–11. It is important to note that, while I agree with Laster’s proposition that texts form ‘the main source of common knowledge about the law’, I downplay the idea of ‘influence’ with its implications of power over the viewer. 10 Rushkoff (1994). 11 Rushkoff (1994), p 51. 12 Rushkoff (1994), p 52. 13 For more on this idea of the public sphere. see McKee (2004). 14 Bennett and Woollacott (1987), pp 55–69. 15 Bennett and Woollacott (1987), p 59. 16 Redhead (1995), p 10. 156 GRIFFITH LAW REVIEW (2006) VOL 15 NO 1 Justice and Law A central consideration in analysing the way law is culturally constructed is the relationship between law and justice.17 However, as Barry notes: Despite more than 2000 years of political theorizing the notion of justice still has no settled meaning: it is the paradigm case of an essentially contested concept. It is not simply that there are fundamental disputes at the normative level … it is the fact that there is so little agreement as to what the concept stands for that causes serious problems.18 In his keynote speech at a Cardozo Law School symposium on deconstruction and law,19 Jacques Derrida claimed that, since justice transcends the legal system, it can never be wholly immanent. Following Plato,20 Derrida views justice as something ‘beyond’ the legal system, something quite apart from legal rights and remedies.21 Indeed, Derrida quotes Montaigne when he states: ‘Laws keep up their good standing not because they are just but because they are laws.’22 This allows for the possibility of justice being something that exceeds or even exists in opposition to the law.23 Justice can therefore be categorised in two ways: as procedural justice (relating to fairness and ensuring that the proper procedures have been followed); and as substantive justice (relating to getting the ‘right’ or ‘correct’ result, even at the expense of some procedural fairness). The classification reveals justice’s relationship with the law. Procedural justice is subordinate to the law. Here justice remains just another aspect of the law, with fairness and closure remaining the true aims of the legal system. In contrast, substantive justice is the aim of the law. Other aspects of the law (like fairness or closure) may necessarily be suspended or ignored to achieve it.24 Clearly, then, the pursuit of justice has a significant impact on the form that law may take. Indeed, Derrida famously pronounced that ‘deconstruction is justice’.25 Legal scholar Douglas Litowitz sees this as ‘laying the 17 Fiebelman (1985). 18 Barry (2000), p 135. 19 Derrida (1992). 20 Balkin (1994). 21 Derrida (1992), p 10. 22 Derrida (1992), p 12. 23 Derrida (1992), p 16. 24 This article is therefore adopting a pragmatic view of justice as the ‘correct’ or ‘fair’ result, predicated on the notion that something is ‘just’ when individuals get what is due to them — a definition which fits both these ideas of justice. In part, the article plays into the debates around moral relativism in accepting that justice does have a different meaning depending on where it is found — though in this case this is produced more by its relationship with law than its social or cultural context. 25 Derrida (1992), p 15. BAINBRIDGE: LAWYERS, JUSTICE AND THE STATE 157 groundwork for … an almost dialectical struggle between law and justice’ 26 — or, more precisely, that ‘the call to do justice to the other is what spurs the deconstructive process into action, and hence the very process of deconstruction is a process of seeking justice’.27 Here, then, the act of seeking justice itself shapes the law, creating instability in the law and resulting in at least two different forms of law, what I have termed modern law and pre- modern law.28 Modern law refers to ‘black letter law’, based around the idea of the Rule of Law. I’ve termed this concept ‘modern law’ because the Rule of Law is itself at the very heart of modernity, both as an important part of the public sphere and as a way of ensuring the continuing maintenance of ‘order’ and ‘certainty’ — two of the central concerns of modernity.29 Modernity’s belief in progress through rationalism resulted in a corresponding rise in the presence of the courtroom and the idea of empirical argumentation as a locus of justice, leading Max Weber30 to conclude that law itself legitimated the modern state.31 The Rule of Law is defined by contrast with the ‘rules of man’ — arbitrary, ad hoc decisions. Its most basic requirements are consistency, through rules fixed in advance, and public knowledge and fairness, through neutral application.32 The modern ideal of law is therefore based around rationality. It aims to provide due process, ensuring fairness and equality. To a certain extent, it also seeks to provide reassurance that the legal system is the best forum for dealing with criminal and civil issues as it ensures objectivity and impartiality. In modern law, then, justice remains procedural in that it is 26 Litowitz (1997), p 97. 27 Litowitz (1997), p 102. 28 This is based in part on Lyotard’s (1985) notion of a ‘multiplicity of justices, each one of them defined in relation to the rules specific to each [language] game’: (1985), p 100, emphasis added. Here I’m suggesting that the intersection of justice and law actually results in a ‘multiplicity of laws’, each based on ‘the rules specific to each game’ — that is, the place of justice in the law. We could include postmodern law here as well, but for reasons of space this article remains focused on pre-modern and modern law. 29 Sarup (1996), p 50, citing Zygmunt Bauman. 30 Max Weber (1991). 31 American legal historian Jerold Auerback (1983) concurs, stating that ‘no longer is it possible to reflect seriously about American culture without accounting for the centrality of law in American history and society’ (p 115). It is certainly valid that Auerback’s argument regarding the centrality of law in modern society also applies, at the very least, to England and Australia as well. We can break down the relationship between law and the modern state further: civil litigation encourages an aggressive form of individualism; criminal law legitimates military power (both foreign and domestic); statute law governs surveillance, both directly and indirectly (through regulation), providing transparency and equality to all citizens; test cases encourage research and development (progress); and the legal system, as a whole, enshrines equality through access and fair representation (at least in principle). 32 Fallon (1997). 158 GRIFFITH LAW REVIEW (2006) VOL 15 NO 1 just another aspect of law, to be considered and balanced against these other requirements. In contrast, a pre-modern ideal of law privileges justice over equality and emotion over rationality, with emotion often viewed as a conduit to the ‘truth’. This ideal of law is ‘pre-modern’ in the sense that it has a connection to the ‘sacred’, the (pre-modern) forms of church law or divine law in ancient societies. Here, kings or clergy were said to have a direct conduit to the will of the divine and therefore came to personify the law themselves.33 In pre-modern law, justice is clearly substantive in that it is the aim of law, overriding concerns of due process or equality. The Lawyer As an officer of the court, and hence a representative of the legal system, the lawyer is one of the most common signifiers of law. In film and television, the lawyer is often presented as the heroic protagonist of the legal drama, the visual antecedent of the legal thriller, because the drama typically comes out of the relationship between the lawyer and the legal system of which they are a part, rather than from the relationship between the lawyer and the criminal.34 A number of Perry Mason (1957–66) episodes bear this out, where Mason has to work against the legal system to prove his client’s innocence. Similarly, in To Kill a Mockingbird (1962), Atticus Finch’s struggle to exonerate Tom Robinson is framed as a struggle by a moral lawyer against a flawed and bigoted justice system. In some instances, legal dramas suggest that professionalism, working within the constraints of the system, can itself be heroic.35 When DAs Richard Bey (Jason Kravits) and Helen Gamble (Lara Flynn Boyle) go to lunch after losing a case on the television series The Practice (1997–2004), Bey reassures Gamble that they are the heroes because they are trying to uphold justice and put away the criminals (an argument often replicated by the DAs in Law & Order (1990– )). The Practice’s defence lawyer Eugene Young (Steve Harris) reminds the lawyers at his firm that their courage to represent unpopular clients makes them heroic — an argument that echoes the sentiments of defence lawyers in films from Compulsion (1959) to In the Name of the Father (1993). Similarly, The Verdict’s (1982) Frank Galvin (Paul Newman) is presented as heroic because he learns how to overcome his alcoholism and depression, work hard and win a case. Here, Galvin’s move toward professionalism is presented as heroic. The lawyers in each of these examples clearly signify the modern ideal of law: their professionalism maintains faith in the legal system; the fact they are heroic simply by discharging their duty, or attempting to discharge their duty, reinforces the need for due process; and the fact that resolution occurs in the courtroom underscores the importance of rational argumentation. But legal 33 See Feldman (2000). 34 Bainbridge (2004). 35 Menkel-Meadow (2001), p 1319. BAINBRIDGE: LAWYERS, JUSTICE AND THE STATE 159 dramas do not form an homogenised discursive whole, and more often than not quite a different form of law is signified. In May 2003, the American Film Institute nominated Atticus Finch (Gregory Peck), the indomitable Southern lawyer of To Kill a Mockingbird, as the greatest hero in the history of motion pictures.36 The main reason given for Finch’s nomination was his role in fighting racial prejudice through his defence of the alleged rapist Tom Robinson. At first glance, Atticus Finch’s victory in To Kill a Mockingbird seems to be an endorsement of the modern ideal of law, signified by a lawyer simply discharging their duty; however, as Simon notes,37 Finch concludes the film by engaging in an obstruction of justice. Sheriff Heck Tate and Finch collude to say Bob Ewell’s death was an accident rather than the act of Boo Radley, who was defending Finch’s children from Ewell’s attack. To be fair, Finch does argue against the sheriff, saying that Radley should go to trial as the killing is justified, but he ultimately concedes Tate’s point that the legal system that has just failed Tom Robinson will most likely fail Boo Radley too.38 Here, then, Finch is clearly not operating as an officer of the court. Justice relies on what Simon terms Finch’s moral pluck — ‘a combination of transgression and resourcefulness in the vindication of justice’.39 In To Kill a Mockingbird, then, justice is found to lie outside and occasionally (as here) in opposition to the legal system. Similarly at other points in the film, Finch is forced to act outside his role as Robinson’s lawyer, standing guard over his gaol cell to protect him from a lynching and engaging in a good amount of detective work to ‘prove’ (though not to the jury’s satisfaction) that Robinson is incapable of the rape ascribed to him. Finch’s nomination as ‘hero’ relies in equal measure on his abilities inside the courtroom and, at certain moments, acting outside or even in opposition to his role as lawyer. Finch therefore incorporates aspects of both the ‘modern’ and ‘pre-modern’ ideals of law — a mixture of rationality and emotion where due process is frequently overridden by the pursuit of substantive justice. Simon pursues this idea of moral pluck through the literary works of John Grisham and the television series LA Law (1986–94)40 — and it is an idea that can be applied to the analysis of what may be thought of as other ‘heroic’ lawyers too, most notably Perry Mason. Originating in Erle Stanley Gardner’s stories in a variety of pulps (including Black Mask magazine) in 1933, Mason always straddled a variety of genres as his tales were part legal procedural and part pulp thriller.41 Perry Mason’s transition to radio (1943–55) marked the 36 Age, 14 June 2003. 37 Simon (2001). 38 The original scene occurs in Harper Lee’s To Kill a Mockingbird (1960) at 286-91. For another discussion of the scene as a justified ‘cover up’, see Atkinson (1999). 39 Simon (2001), p 422. 40 Simon (2001). 41 Mason’s transition from pulp to courtroom procedural is demonstrable in a comparison of The Case of the Velvet Claws (1933), which takes place entirely outside the courtroom, and The Case of the Sulky Girl (1934), which features a 160 GRIFFITH LAW REVIEW (2006) VOL 15 NO 1 addition of another genre, soap opera, that was later abandoned for the long- running television series (1957–66) featuring Raymond Burr, from which the character is probably best remembered.42 Some critics have been quick to dismiss Perry Mason’s importance as a legal drama because of the inordinate amount of time Mason spends on detective-work,43 and the fact that he loses only once (and then only because the defendant refuses to reveal information that would save her). I prefer to think of Perry Mason as one of the most subversive of all law shows because of its implicit idea that a lawyer discharging their duty is not enough to be heroic. As with Atticus Finch, to be heroic necessarily requires a combination of legal and extra-legal action.44 This idea of combination, of justice requiring a combination of the legal and the extra-legal, is important. Mason’s victories depend on both his legwork (usually through private investigator Paul Drake (William Hopper)) outside the courtroom and his devastating cross-examinations within. Indeed, the trademark courtroom confessions which conclude almost every episode of the television series are only used irregularly in the novels. These confessions seem indicative of a desire to reassert the idea that justice (as represented by the confession of guilt) is ultimately found in the courtroom, even if such a finding is reached through a combination of legal and extra-legal means. So, while substantive justice is clearly Perry Mason’s aim, finding the ‘correct’ result in the courtroom also provides some measure of reassurance in the modern legal system as the appropriate forum. Collins and Javna45 see Perry Mason’s structure — of a crime, an innocent accused, Mason and company engaging in detective work to find the truth and a concluding courtroom showdown — as moving ‘beyond formula into ritual’. At its heart is this notion that discharging one’s duty as a defence attorney (defending one’s client to the best of one’s ability) is not enough to be heroic. Rather, it is necessary to go one step further and uncover who is actually guilty. Furthermore, any amount of rule-breaking (and occasional law- breaking) is presented as justified in light of Mason’s end result; in The Case lengthy courtroom interrogation. Mason carried on for 82 novels, a few short stories and a novella before crossing over to films in 1934. 42 The soap opera elements were spun off into another television series, The Edge of Night (1956), which utilised the same radio cast with new character names. The Perry Mason television series returned in 1973–74 with a different cast as The New Adventures of Perry Mason. Finally, there was a series of telemovies, The Perry Mason Mysteries (1985–93), marking Raymond Burr’s return to the role which ran until (just after) his death. 43 For example, Steven Bochco, creator of LA Law, describes Perry Mason as a mystery series; Collins and Javna (1988) classify it as a private eye series. 44 This was highlighted in the Perry Mason newspaper strip (1950–54), where Mason was continually reminding his clients ‘I’m a lawyer … not a policeman’ (The Case of the Innocent Thief) or ‘you need a detective, not a lawyer’ (The Case of the Nervous Horse) — and, of course, in both these cases Mason ends up lending a hand (Mason, 1989). 45 Collins and Javna (1988), p 29 BAINBRIDGE: LAWYERS, JUSTICE AND THE STATE 161 of the Curious Bride, for example, Mason ‘bought an apartment building so he could legally change the locks and doorbells and screw up DA (Hamilton) Burger’s evidence’.46 This is a ritual that is replicated in later series like America’s Matlock (1986–95), Australia’s short-lived Case for the Defence (1974) and, again to a lesser extent, the UK series Rumpole of the Bailey (1978–92) (in Rumpole’s occasional interest in finding who really committed the crime). In some ways, The Practice can also be classified as following this trend. Sometimes the defence lawyers do track down the real culprit or, in a neat inverse of the Perry Mason tactic of breaking down the guilty party on the stand, accuse someone else of the crime. The lawyers on The Practice, Thomas suggests,47 are therefore heroic ‘in the sense of going beyond their typical call of duty’.48 More recently, the British legal drama Judge John Deed (2004– ) presents a heroic judge in much the same mould as Finch and Mason. The promotional literature describes him as ‘contemptuous of the rules created by an archaic and out of touch bureaucracy, his passion for justice and maverick approach set him at odds with the Lord Chancellor’s department’.49 Deed (Martin Shaw) is frequently seen to ‘transgress’ the laws of his office by giving the accused another chance to speak before the jury, fraternising with the defence barrister and even conducting private searches on judges he considers may be corrupt. While all of these men remain officers of the court, frequently they must act outside the scope of their role as a lawyer — and sometimes in direct contravention of it — to achieve justice. This is a clear endorsement of the pre- modern ideal of law, where substantive justice becomes the primary motivator, even where other legal rights and duties must be suspended to achieve it. As such, these lawyers in the Finch-Mason-Deed mould represent the first slide in the signification of law away from the modern rule of law and towards a more pre-modern conception. The Police Procedural The distinction between the modern and pre-modern forms of law is well made in Orson Welles’ classic film Touch of Evil (1958, reconstructed 1998). The film depicts the struggle between ‘modern’ chairman of the Pan American Narcotics Commission, Ramon Miguel ‘Mike’ Vargas (Charlton Heston), and ‘pre-modern’ corrupt policeman Hank Quinlan (Orson Welles) in the Mexican border town of Los Robles (itself a metaphor for the larger issue of the treatment of Mexicans by American law enforcement). Motivated by the unsolved murder of his wife, described as ‘the last killer that ever got out of my hands’, Quinlan is corrupt insofar as he plants evidence on suspects he 46 (Collins and Javna (1988), p 30. 47 Thomas (2001). 48 Thomas (2001), p 1511. This means The Practice is advancing two ways for lawyers to be heroic — one is by discharging their duty, the other is by going beyond their duty. 49 Channel Seven website. 162 GRIFFITH LAW REVIEW (2006) VOL 15 NO 1 considers guilty of a crime. In one of his early encounters with Vargas, Quinlan juxtaposes the policeman’s role quite clearly against the lawyer’s: Adair: Hank’s a born lawyer, you know. Quinlan: Lawyer! I’m no lawyer. All a lawyer cares about is the law! Vargas: Captain! You are a policeman, aren’t you? Quinlan: Mmm … Aren’t you? You don’t seem to be very fond of the job. Vargas: There are plenty of soldiers who don’t like war. Quinlan: Hmmm … Vargas: It’s a dirty job enforcing the law, but it’s what we’re supposed to be doing, isn’t it? Quinlan: I don’t know about you. But when a murderer’s loose, I’m supposed to catch him. The way Quinlan places the capture of the suspect above due process clearly marks him as a signifier of the pre-modern ideal of law. Indeed, Quinlan’s frequent comments that ‘we’ll get evidence’ point to the way he fabricates evidence as a way of proving the guilt of the people he suspects. As far as he’s concerned, he never framed anybody but rather was ‘aiding justice’ — that is, getting the ‘correct’ result. The point is well made when Vargas tries to expose Quinlan’s corruption, culminating in the quotation that heads this article: Quinlan: Our friend Vargas has some very special ideas about police procedure. He seems to think it don’t matter whether a killer is hanged or not, as long as we obey the fine print … Vargas: Well, no, captain … Quinlan: … in the rule books. Vargas: … I don’t think a policeman should work like a dog-catcher … Quinlan: No? Vargas: … putting criminals behind bars. No! In any free country … Quinlan: Aw … Vargas: … a policeman is supposed to enforce the law, and the law protects the guilty as well as the innocent. Quinlan: Our job is tough enough. Vargas: It’s supposed to be. It has to be tough. The policeman’s job is only easy in a police state. That’s the whole point, captain. Who is the boss, the cop or the law? For the purposes of this article, Quinlan’s corruption is less important than his assertion that the police generally signify a pre-modern ideal of law.50 50 While this paper accepts Barthes’ and Foucault’s notion of ‘the death of the author’, this also seems in keeping with Welles’ original intention. There is evidence that Welles’ work in Touch of Evil was inspired by the beating and blinding of black naval veteran Isaac Woodward Jr by police in South Carolina. On the Orson Welles Sketchbook (BBC-TV, 7 May 1955), Welles comments: ‘I BAINBRIDGE: LAWYERS, JUSTICE AND THE STATE 163 Indeed, as if to prove the point, the very modern Vargas himself has moved towards a pre-modern ideal of law by the end of the film when he is reduced to illegally taping Quinlan to prove his guilt. In police procedurals, films and series which focus on the workings of police, the signifier of law presented is either ‘the police force’51 or ‘the individual policeman’.52 These signifiers represent another slide away from the modern ideal of law where rational inquiry is frequently abandoned in favour of instinct or emotion, where individual rights are suspended for the good of the community and crime’s ‘causes and definitions [become] self-evident, that criminals are easily recognisable and the punishments that we should give them, obvious’.53 Ironically then, despite the police and the state being profoundly modern institutions, the police are signifiers of a pre-modern ideal of law. The classic example here is the film Dirty Harry (1971). The title foregrounds, even celebrates, Harry Callahan’s (Clint Eastwood) ‘dirtiness’, his lack of respect for the legal system in favour of doing whatever is deemed necessary to control crime (here, bringing the sniper Scorpio (Andrew Robinson) to justice). This is exemplified in a scene Chase describes where Harry clashes with DA William T Rothko over the abuse of a suspect’s rights.54 Ultimately it is Harry who delivers his own transcendent justice with the (now immortal) quip: ‘Do I feel lucky? Well, do you? Punk?’ As Scorpio reaches for his gun, Harry blows him away. His final rejection of the modern ideal of law is revealed at the film’s end when Harry skips his police badge across the water. Harry becomes a signifier of pre-modern law through his desire to protect community rather than individual (Scorpio’s) rights, through his ‘direct line’ to the truth (appointing himself Scorpio’s executioner) and through his often complete lack of accountability (his rejection of modern law at the movie’s conclusion). Of course, police procedurals are not always uncritical of police as exemplars of the law. Some foreground ‘the ideological and coercive work of the police’55 as evident in series featuring ruthless or just plain corrupt cops like The Sweeney (1975–78), The Shield (2002) and recent seasons of The Bill. Similarly, there are many hybrid forms of the police procedural, creating an ever-changing signifier of ‘the law’ applicable to series as diverse as Cagney am willing to admit that the policeman has a difficult job, a very hard job. But it’s the essence of our society that a policeman’s job should be hard. He’s there to protect the free citizen, not to chase criminals — that’s an incidental part of his job.’ (quoted in Comito 1985), which seems to elucidate the difference between pre-modern and modern law, if not using that exact terminology. 51 As in the UK The Bill (1984– ), Australia’s Blue Heelers (1994– ) or the US Hill Street Blues (1981–87). 52 Be it America’s Columbo (1971–77), Australia’s Boney (1972–73) or England’s Inspector Morse (1987–2000). 53 Grant (1992), p 58. 54 Chase (2002), pp 73–74. 55 Clarke (1986, 1992). 164 GRIFFITH LAW REVIEW (2006) VOL 15 NO 1 and Lacey (1982–88), Cracker (1993– ) and Inspector Morse.56 However, common to all of these series is a narrative Toby Miller identifies as belonging to the detective genre but which is just as applicable to the police procedural: The villain and the detective depend on each other through an overarching third term: the law and its embodiment in the state, which one must elude and the other convince that justice be meted out.57 It is this conception of ‘the state’ that is important here — a ‘state’ that, despite its legal implications,58 for the most part is seen to exist without the presence of lawyers. This disenchantment with the legal system is best demonstrated by what is not shown. Most police procedurals are discrete. They end with the capture of the criminal, the implication being that it is here that justice occurs, sparing us the intricacies of the legal system, its failures and its delays. As Friedman notes,59 popular culture often displays an ‘impatience with technicality and procedure’ through its depiction of technicalities as ‘obstructions to justice’. The interrogation room has come to replace the courtroom on police procedurals as the locus of ‘truth’ and ‘justice’ in series like NYPD Blue (1993–2005), Homicide: Life on the Street (1993–99) and more recently Law & Order: Criminal Intent (2001– ). NYPD Blue’s Andy Sipowicz (Dennis Franz) regularly abuses and slaps suspects. Greg Medavoy (Gordon Clapp) strikes a suspect with a telephone book. Homicide’s Frank Pembleton (Andre Braugher) engages suspects in complex mind games, whittling away at them until they crack. Criminal Intent’s Robert Goran (Vincent D’Onofrio) does the same. As Sterne notes,60 all do this without reference to a code of conduct (like the Amnesty International 1996 Report) and always without the presence of a lawyer. Most often, suspects are tricked into not calling their lawyers in the belief that it will ‘be easier’ for them if they don’t. Here the policeman becomes the transcendental justice figure, as aptly demonstrated in an episode of Law & Order: Criminal Intent.61 During the police room interrogation, the terrorist Ethan says: ‘I was sent by God.’ To which Detective Eames (Kathryn Zerbe) (Goran’s partner) replies: ‘So were we.’ The production of a confession replaces the verdict as the moment of catharsis in these dramas, providing both resolution and a sense of justice, with detectives often rewarding themselves afterwards for getting ‘results’. In the police procedural, then, it is the arrest of the suspect that provides narrative 56 Creeber (2001), pp 19–23. 57 Creeber (2001), p 18, emphasis added. 58 Following on from Weber’s (1992) idea that law legitimated the modern state, by ‘state’ I refer to a legal association, a ‘juridicially organized nation, or a nation organized for action under legal rules’ (Baker 1951). Baker therefore sees the state as existing for law: ‘it exists in and through law: we may even say it exists as law’. 59 Friedman (2000), p 556. 60 Sterne (2000). 61 18 March 2003. BAINBRIDGE: LAWYERS, JUSTICE AND THE STATE 165 closure, bypassing the legal system (and its attendant requirements) with a ‘Book ’em Dano’ (as Jack Lord provides in Hawaii Five-O (1968–80) and a cut to the end credits. The Lawyer and the Policeman When lawyer characters are present, they are often treated with at best a healthy distrust and scepticism, and at worst outright hostility. Lawyers are portrayed as impediments to the police investigation; the rights of the accused are seen to stand in the way of the pursuit of justice. But, as Toby Miller notes, there is one way in which the lawyer can be included in the police procedural: the police need togetherness to survive rather than utility-maximising individualism. This affective bond allows protagonists to maintain a sense of self as they are sent into situations that frequently bear no relationship to their own existence.62 Therefore, the only way lawyer characters are given any sort of respect or place in these series is if they become a part of the police community. In NYPD Blue, for example, ADA Sylvia Costas (Sharon Lawrence) is only really accepted as part of the community when she commences a relationship with Detective Sipowicz (Dennis Franz). After this, she is seen in more domestic situations. Similarly on Hill Street Blues, Public Defender Joyce Davenport (Veronica Hammel) is only accepted as a part of the system through her relationship with Captain Frank Furillo (Daniel J Travanti). Hill Street Blues consistently demonstrated Davenport’s acceptance into the community in the way most episodes ended with Furillo and Davenport in bed, rather than through her work in court (which remained rarely seen).63 An interesting example occurs in the Australian series Stingers Undercover (2000–04), which introduced a lawyer character, Ingrid Burton (Rebecca Gibney), in its 2002–03 season to capitalise on the interest in the American legal series then airing on Australian television.64 Stingers Undercover revolves around the activities of a police undercover unit, the principal member of which is Peter Church (Peter Phelps). At the end of the 2001 season, Church’s team-mate Oscar Stone is killed by Kevin Conrad. The 2002 season opens with the episode Collateral Damage, depicting Conrad’s trial and the introduction of Ingrid Burton as Kevin Conrad’s attorney.65 62 Quoted in Creeber (2001), p 18. 63 Indeed, during the fifth season (1984), Davenport briefly switched sides, becoming an ADA and prosecuting cases (before returning to the Public Defenders Office at season’ s end). 64 This was part of a trend that included the launch of Channel 7’s legal comedy Marshall Law and ABC’s legal/medical drama MDA 65 Burton is also constructed as very sexual. She’s tall, her gown hangs open to enable point-of-view shots of her legs and she wears her wig well back on her head to make the most of her long, blonde hair. By way of explanation, prosecutor Dawson Lynch (Christopher Gabaldi) tells Church: ‘Burton is a very astute lawyer … she’s very persuasive with the jury.’ 166 GRIFFITH LAW REVIEW (2006) VOL 15 NO 1 Burton is cast very much at odds with the undercover unit. She represents the man who killed their partner and seems to take pleasure in her job. Here and in subsequent appearances, Burton will not only represent someone whom the undercover unit is investigating but will actively encourage them to sue the unit for some perceived wrongdoing.66 Burton’s first appearance also features the first of many exchanges with Church: Church: Ever wonder if it’s worth it — defending these low lifes? Burton: Don’t take it personally. It was a court appointment. Church: So that’s your excuse? Burton: I do my job, Peter. The difference is I do it within the law. Burton falls back on this line ‘It’s my job’ to defend her role in the legal system time and again. In many ways, it follows the approach of Eugene Young (The Practice), Compulsion and In the Name of the Father (as outlined above), where being heroic is simply discharging one’s duties. ‘I’m a lawyer, it’s what I do’ she says in Breakdown and again, ‘It’s my job’ in Partners in Crime, but it is in Scratch me Lucky, as she begins a sexual relationship with Peter following a chance encounter in a bar, that she sets out to explain her position: Burton: It’s my job. Church: Defending slime? Burton: Everyone’s entitled to the best possible defence. It’s the only way we can protect the innocent. Church: But you know [your client’s] guilty don’t you? Burton: Guilt’s for the jury to determine. I’m just an officer of the court. Burton is therefore a signifier of the modern ideal of law. She is heroic simply by virtue of doing her work, discharging her duty and ensuring due process is followed.67 This particular episode ends with Church and Burton in bed together. Although some of their adversarial nature remains visible in the fact that Church is secretly taping confessions Burton makes (which could lead to perjury charges in the future), it is the first indication that Burton’s role may change. Like Sylvia Costas and Joyce Davenport, she starts being seen in social settings (The Whole Truth) and visits Church at his headquarters 66 As in the episode Separation Anxiety, where Burton encourages Miles Vanderhoeven (Tony Richards) to sue both the unit and Angie Piper (severally) for negligence. 67 Burton also accepts that this sets her apart from Church. In the episode Payback, she tells Church: ‘You think we’re on opposite sides don’t you? Professionally, docially, morally’. This neatly delineates the differences between the modern and pre-modern ideals of law they signify. BAINBRIDGE: LAWYERS, JUSTICE AND THE STATE 167 (Payback). While there is some lingering confusion over their professional and private lives, Burton is more readily accepted into the Stingers team, first to assist the team in catching the escaped Conrad (The Whole Truth) and then helping Angie Piper when Church disappears (Breakdown). Also noticeable is that Burton’s ‘I’m a lawyer’ routine is starting to break down, as is tellingly revealed in Partners in Crime, where the following exchange occurs: Church: Well, I’m a cop, you’re a lawyer. Burton: Doesn’t that bother you? That we can’t be friends with each other? … If you had any evidence you’d lay charges [against Burton’s client Stig Endquist (Tim Robertson)]. Church: And you’d defend him. Burton: It’s my job. Something that you’re making really bloody difficult for me to do. Here she is expressing some doubt over her position. Her signification of the modern ideal of law has been problematised. Indeed, her position has shifted so much over the course of the season that by the last episode she is actively helping Church in his operation against Endquist, a position that leaves her own life in jeopardy in the season cliffhanger. Burton has become part of the undercover community. Through a sexual relationship, she has been accepted into that community and then subsequently proves herself as part of that community. She has become a sliding signifier of law, moving almost completely away from the modern ideal she first signified toward a pre- modern one. Endquist’s individual rights, to representation, to due process, are suspended for the communal good. Following her rescue at the start of the next season and the end of her affair with Church, Burton proves her ‘pre-modernity’ by performing a ‘sting’ herself. Burton empties a number of Endquist’s bank accounts, effectively exposing his schemes and bankrupting him (thus bringing him to justice) and also supporting herself as she goes into hiding. Justice is achieved, Endquist is arrested and Church grins as Burton (literally) flies off into the sunset; Burton has become a ‘stinger’ too. She now embodies a pre-modern ideal of law, completely removed from the modern ideal she once signified. Burton, Costas and Davenport are all indicative of a trend in police procedurals: that, to be accepted into the police community, the lawyer must necessarily sacrifice part of their modern role as lawyer and embrace a more ‘pre-modern’ role.68 When this does not happen, the lawyer remains a fringe figure, largely obstructionist and often reduced to a caricature or stereotype, symptomatic of the way some elements of modernity — like fairness and equality — are consistently sidelined in police procedurals. 68 It is notable, of course, that all of these examples are female and their acceptance begins with a sexual relationship with the male police characters. 168 GRIFFITH LAW REVIEW (2006) VOL 15 NO 1 Government Thrillers While the lawyer and the policeman are still perhaps the most common signifiers of law, increasingly, in the wake of the September 11, 2001 attacks on the World Trade Center and the Pentagon, a new signifier of law has been appearing with increasing regularity — the government agent. The government agent features in the American series Alias (2001– ), Without a Trace (2002– ) and 24 (2001– ) and the English series Spooks (2002– )69 and, perhaps most famously, the James Bond, Mission Impossible and Jason Bourne film franchises.70 The government agent is a signifier of law that slides still further away from the modern ideal of law and towards a purely pre-modern one because not only is justice the perceived aim, it is pursued with few limitations. The threat of death (as classically represented by James Bond’s licence to kill) or torture (as evidenced by Jack Bauer’s actions in 24 or Michael Vaughn’s actions in Alias) are both presented as justifiable ways of achieving substantive justice. Once again, we can see that this is a significant shift if we compare, for example, the interrogation scenes from the Law & Order: SVU Season 6 episode Rage to the interrogation scenes in 24. In Law & Order: SVU, Detective Elliot Stabler (Christopher Meloni) is seen setting up the interrogation room for Gordon Rickett (Matthew Modine), a child rapist he tried to convict 14 years earlier and who he now suspects has murdered a young girl. Stabler ensures the lights flicker, Rickett’s chair is uneven and has the heat turned up. He does everything to make Rickett as uncomfortable as possible. He even has food and drink provided in the hope that it will force Rickett to use the toilet. In contrast, 24 features Counter Terrorism Unit (CTU) agent Jack Bauer (Kiefer Sutherland) shooting suspects in knee caps, squeezing bullet wounds and making it appear he has executed someone — all presented as legitimate means of obtaining information from a suspect. The signifier of law has therefore shifted from the intimidation and threats (of the police procedural) to actual physical torture. As television writer Clive Thompson notes: this crop of smart thrillers … began twisting the thumbscrews right after 9/11, three years before Guantanamo and Abu Ghraib [the facilities where mistreatment of terrorist detainees occurred] hit the headlines. Alias launched nineteen days after the World Trade Center attacks … The shows are unusually good at capturing the dark sensuality of 69 Spooks is known as MI-5 in America. 70 At the time of writing, there are 26 Bond films (the latest is 2006’s Casino Royale), three Mission Impossible films and two Jason Bourne films — The Bourne Identity (2002) and The Bourne Supremacy (2004). It should also be noted that the government agent/spy genre is also prevalent in children’s entertainment, including the film series Spy Kids, Agent Cody Banks and Alex Rider and the television series James Bond Jr and Kim Possible. This is the only signifier covered by this paper that also features in a children’s format. While they are more restrained than their adult counterparts, there is still little respect for the modern ideal of law in these children’s series. BAINBRIDGE: LAWYERS, JUSTICE AND THE STATE 169 torture: the Cartesian horror of being trapped in a vulnerable body, the sub-dom relationship of the torturer and his victim.71 Most interesting for Thompson is that often ‘it’s the good guys in the tormentor’s seat’72 and they are celebrated as heroic in their endeavours to garner the truth from their suspects. Jack Bauer, for example, is referred to as heroic a number of times in 24, no more so than in the final episode of Season 4 where the head of CTU, defending Bauer’s decision to raid a Chinese consulate for information (killing a consular official in the process) says: ‘We’d be burying a million Americans now if it weren’t for Jack Bauer. He’s a hero.’ Here we have a clear statement of the pre-modern ideal of law; the ‘right’ result, the ‘correct’ result, has occurred — and justifies whatever means were used. Justice and preventing terrorism are conflated into one and the same thing. In these government thrillers, as in the police procedural, lawyers are again sidelined and seen as an impediment to the delivery of substantive justice. In 24, for example, a terrorist suspect calls ‘Amnesty Global’ to get a lawyer and ensure due process applies. Here the point is well made: terrorists are about to get their hands on a nuclear warhead, millions of American lives are in the balance and Bauer believes that only this suspect can help them. He needs to make him talk, by any means necessary. The lawyer therefore becomes an impediment to justice. To drive the point home, Bauer even asks his superiors: ‘Why won’t he let us do our jobs?’ Unlike the police procedural, there is no provision for the lawyer to join the community here. But while Bauer is diegetically celebrated as a hero, most of the last episode of 24’s fourth season is given over to exploring the repercussions of the government’s meddling. The Chinese demand Bauer be turned over to them, President Logan doesn’t authorise Bauer’s murder but certainly won’t do anything to stop it, and the national hero becomes a problem that needs to be disposed of. What is at issue here is best expressed by (former) President David Palmer (Dennis Haysbert), who will not allow Bauer to be turned over to the Chinese because ‘they’ll put you on trial to propagandise about American interference’. It is this ‘making visible’ that the government fears, and to some extent it is this ‘making visible’ (of the liminality of law, of the ways in which suspects are intimidated and questioned) that forms the basis of the intellectual work these series are engaged in. As Thompson notes,73 ‘the fact that such shows cater to our creepier revenge fantasies isn’t reason to condemn them; for all their flash and gore, they can also be a step toward a moral debate’ — this is an idea to which I return below. The presentation of torture as policy in series like 24 demonstrates how far the signifier of law has slid, as crime fighters (arguably the rubric under which lawyers, police and government agents all fall) become ever more brutal in their efforts to achieve justice and the state suffers the repercussions of its endless meddling. 71 Thompson (2005). 72 Thompson (2005). 73 Thompson (2005). 170 GRIFFITH LAW REVIEW (2006) VOL 15 NO 1 The increasing prevalence of ‘the state’ as the signifier of law in popular culture parallels the increasing intervention of ‘the state’ in the real world, particularly post-September 11 and particularly in the area of proactive law. Here, there has been a notable expansion and concentration of power in the executive74 and a move towards interventionist justice. In the United States, the Patriot Act’s75 expansion of the investigative powers of the Federal Bureau of Investigation (FBI) has led to accusations of racial profiling and discrimination that are defended as proactive measures. The ongoing ‘war on terror’ is also couched in terms of spreading freedom in the world and therefore ‘an urgent requirement of our nation’s security’,76 thereby demanding intervention. In Australia, proactive anti-terrorist legislation aims to broaden the definition of a terrorist act to enable prosecution of people who are plotting an attack (ABC News Online). Similarly interventionist ASIO Legislation Amendment Act 2006 amendments to the National Security Information (Criminal and Civil Proceedings) Act 2004 would enable the Australian Security Intelligence Office (ASIO) to commandeer information from journalists.77 In all of these Acts, we see a continuing shift away from the modern ideal of law with its emphasis on due process, fairness and a right to trial toward a pre-modern ideal of law where individual rights are suspended and justice is prioritised. Part of the problem in legislating against terrorism seems to be in defining the term ‘terrorism’ itself. There remains no accepted definition of terrorism at international law. More particularly, the problem arises in distinguishing acts of terrorism from an armed struggle waged by national liberation movements. The United States, for example, defined the September 11 attacks as acts of war rather than crimes outside a war context which led to terrorism being treated as sui generis (of its own kind) rather than as a crime under existing modern law. This encourages the use of the metaphor ‘war on terror’, with the word ‘war’ itself justifying the use of ‘emergency powers’, the ‘suspension’ of certain liberties and the demarcation of a clear beginning (an act of war like the September 11 attacks), rather than politically contextualising the attacks or responding through the modern legal system — as a number of European countries did. In the United States, there is therefore a shift towards a pre- modern ideal of law which requires new methods to achieve increasingly nebulous ideas of substantive justice. Indeed, this shift toward the pre-modern is articulated by a number of sources. For example, the Justice Department and the FBI blamed their intelligence failures regarding the September 11 attacks on their over-reliance 74 Pillar (2005) notes that this is very much a product of the times. Post Watergate and the Pike and Church committees there had been a curtailing or controlling of executive power rather than an expansion (6). 75 Full Citation: The `Uniting and Strengthening America by Providing Appropriate Tools Required to Intercept and Obstruct Terrorism (USA PATRIOT ACT) Act of 2001’ (HR 3162). 76 (Bush 2005), 77 Fifth Estate (2005). BAINBRIDGE: LAWYERS, JUSTICE AND THE STATE 171 on a criminal justice (modern) approach to counter-terrorism.78 The ‘pre- modernity’ of the state’s approach is underscored by the frequent restatement of the US administration’s aim to ‘bring terrorists to justice for their crimes’,79 which deliberately highlights ‘justice’ rather than ‘trial’. As noted earlier, in all of these sources, justice and preventing terrorism are equated as being one and the same. Perhaps the greatest irony is that, as German notes: ‘Terrorist groups almost never refer to themselves as terrorists, but rather as soldiers, revolutionaries, holy warriors’;80 therefore, terrorists themselves are enacting a pre-modern form of law, with clear links back to the sacred and the belief that substantive justice is on their side. The line between terrorist and hero therefore becomes a matter of perspective, and this serves as a reminder of how nebulous a concept substantive justice truly is. Finch and Mason’s transgressions are only justified by their client’s innocence, Stabler and Burton by the suspect’s guilt, Vargas by Quinlan’s corruption and (arguably) Bauer by the terrorists’ imminent attack. The further the signifier slides away from the modern rule of law, the more difficult it becomes to justify a ‘hero’s’ actions. Conclusion The popular media are alternatively dismissed as liberal (and therefore unceasingly critical of right-wing policy) or conservative (and therefore controlled by big business interests who use the media to hegemonically reinforce their private opinions). But when we take the time to study popular culture’s signifiers of law (from Atticus Finch through to Jack Bauer), we find instead some quite complex intellectual work being undertaken. First, they make visible the mutability of law as term of definition and the commensurate change in government policy this permits. As Thompson notes: ‘For the past three years shows like Alias, 24 and MI-5 [Spooks] have provided a perverse mirror of the real-life response to terror. They’ve reflected, and sometimes eerily predicted, the rise of torture as a government policy.’81 Thus, while the Guatanamo military tribunals are presented as the public face of state law (merging war and crime into one), popular culture makes visible other less popular state policies — including extra-judicial detention, intimidation and torture — by making them the basis of fictional narratives and bringing them into the public sphere, via the popular media, for wider dissemination. are, in Redhead’s terms,82 exposing the ‘(legal) fiction’ that is presented as ‘legal authority’. Second, popular culture promotes debate about the relationship between law and justice and the balance involved in preserving human rights while protecting security interests. 78 9/11 Commission Report (2004), p 423. 79 US Department of State (2004), p ix. 80 German (2005), p 11. 81 Thompson (2005). 82 Redhead (1995), p 10. 172 GRIFFITH LAW REVIEW (2006) VOL 15 NO 1 Certainly Rushkoff’s idea that popular culture is ‘the place for us to evaluate our rules and customs’83 seems to be being borne out. Bob Cochrane, co-creator of 24, has publicly stated that one of the series’ roles is to explore debates around torture, law and justice84 and in this, at least, it appears to have been successful.85 The signifier of law, from lawyer to policeman to government agent, has slid further and further away from the modern rule of law towards an increasingly transcendent and interventionist pursuit of justice. In so doing these signifiers continue to interrogate the law and push the boundaries of what law can be, well beyond the relatively limited and circumscribed space of the courtroom towards increasingly problematic pre-modern notions of ‘justice’ in the wider society. It is a form of intellectual work similar to the notion of ‘work[ing] at the limits of what the rules permit, in order to invent new moves’ that Lyotard advances,86 not only moving the law closer to justice but also promoting debate about how law and justice work together in the wider culture. Re fe re nc e s Secon dar y Sou rc es ABC News Online 2005. ‘Legislation to Broaden Definition of Terrorist Act’, 3 November, www.abc.net.au/news/newsitems/200511/s1496527.html Douglas E Abrams (1998) ‘Picket Fences’ in Robert M Jarvis and Paul R Joseph (eds), Prime Time Law, Carolina Academic Press. Rob Atkinson (1999) ‘Lucifer’s Fiasco: Lawyers, Liars and L’Affaire Lewinsky’ 68 Fordham Law Review 567. Jerold S Auerback (1983) Justice Without Law? Oxford University Press. Jason Bainbridge (2003) ‘Discovering the Law Again: John Grisham, Ed Stevens and the Postmaterial Lawyer’ 30 The Australian Journal of Communication 15. Ernest Baker (1951) Principles of Social and Political Theory, Oxford University Press. Jack Balkin (1994) ‘Transcendental Deconstruction, Transcendental Justice’ 92 Michigan Law Review 1131. Jack Balkin (1987) ‘Deconstructive Practice and Legal Theory’ 96 Yale Law Journal 743. Norman Bary (2000) An Introduction to Modern Political Theory, 4th edn, Macmillan. Roland Barthes (1972) ‘Myth Today’ in Mythologies, Noonday Press. Tony Bennett and Janet Woollacott (1987) Bond and Beyond: The Political Career of a Popular Hero, Methuen. 83 Rushkoff’s (1994), p 52. 84 Thompson (2005). 85 Certainly 24 has achieved this. The Council of American Islamic Relations (CAIR) and a number of other groups complained about the representation of Muslims in Series 4, leading to the screening of ads reminding viewers that most Muslims are good people. 86 Lyotard (1985), p 100. BAINBRIDGE: LAWYERS, JUSTICE AND THE STATE 173 George W Bush (2005) ‘Second Inaugural Address’, www.whitehouse,gov/news/releases/2005/01/20050120-3.html. Bill Carter 1997. ‘Tracking Down Viewers Till They’re Captured: Stars Come and Go, but NBC’s Law & Order Plugs Away’, New York Times, 19 February, p C11. Anthony Chase 2002. Movies on Trial: The Legal System on the Silver Screen, The New Press. Alan Clarke (1986) ‘This is Not the Boy Scouts’: Television Police Series and Definitions of Law and Order’ in Tony Bennett et al (eds), Popular Culture and Social Relations, Open University. Max Allan Collins and John Javna (1988) The Best of Crime and Detective TV, Harmony Books. Terry Comito (1998 [1985]) Touch of Evil — Orson Welles, director, Rutgers. Glen Creeber (2001) The Television Genre Book, British Film Institute. Jonathan Culler (1976) Saussure, Fontana. Peter Dalghren (1995) Television and the Public Sphere: Citizenship, Democracy and the Media, Sage. Richard Delgado (1993) ‘Discussion’ 45 Stanley Law Review 1671. Jacques Derrida (1982) Margins of Philosophy, trans Alan Bass University of Chicago Press. Jacques Derrida (1992) ‘Force of Law: The “Mystical Foundation of Authority”’ in Drucilla Cornell, Michael Rosenfield and David G Carlson (eds), Deconstruction and the Possibility of Justice, Routledge. Jacques Derrida (1994) Specters of Marx, trans Peggy Kamuf, Routledge. Ferdinand De Saussure, Ferdinand (1983 [1916]) Course in General Linguistics, trans Roy Harris, Duckworth. Ronald Dworkin (1998 [1985]) Law’s Empire, Hart. Richard H Fallon Jr (1997) ‘“The Rule of Law” as a Concept in Constitutional Discourse’ 97 Columbia Law Review 1. James K. Feibleman (1985) Justice, Law and Culture, Martinus Nijhoff. Stephen Feldman (2000) American Legal Through from Premodernism to Postmodernism: An Intellectual Voyage, Oxford University Press. Fifth Estate, The (2005) ‘Sunset on Media Freedom?’ http://fifth.estate.rmit.edu.au/sunset-on-media-freedom.php. John Fiske (1982) Introduction to Communication Studies, Methuen. Lawrence Friedman (2000) ‘Lexitainment: Legal Process as Theatre’ 50 De Paul Law Review 539. Clifford Geertz (1983) Local Knowledge: Further Essays in Interpretive Anthropology, Basic Books. Michael German (2005) ‘Squaring the Error’, in Law vs War: Competing Approaches to Fighting Terrorism: Conference Report. July, www.carlisle.army.mil/ssi. Steven Gillers (1989) ‘Taking LA Law More Seriously’ 98 Yale Law Journal 1608. Judith Grant (1992) ‘Prime Time Crime: Television Portrayals of Law Enforcement’ 15 Journal of American Culture 58. Jurgen Habermas (1997) ‘The Public Sphere’ in Robert E. Goodin and Philip Pettit (eds), Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Anthology, Blackwell. Bob Harris (1996) Politics and the Rise of the Press, Britain and France 1620–1800, Routledge. Herbert Hart (1995 [1961]) The Concept of Law, rev edn, Clarendon Press. John Hartley (1999) Uses of Television, Routledge. Terence Hawkes (1977) Structuralism and Semiotics, Methuen. 174 GRIFFITH LAW REVIEW (2006) VOL 15 NO 1 Agnes Heller (1999) A Theory of Modernity, Blackwell. Dawn Keetley (1998) ‘Law and Order’ in Robert M Jarvis and Paul R Joseph (eds), Prime Time Law, Carolina Academic Press. Kathy Laster (2000) The Drama of the Courtroom, Federation Press. Douglas Litowitz (1997) Postmodern Philosophy and Law, University Press of Kansas. Douglas Litowitz (2000) ‘In Defence of Postmodernism’ 4 Green Bag 39. Jean-Francois Lyotard (1984) The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge, Manchester University Press. Jean-Francois Lyotard (1985) Just Gaming, trans Wlad Godzich with Jean-Loup Thebaud, University of Minnesota Press. Jean-Francois Lyotard (1988) The Differend: Phrases in Dispute, trans Georges Van Den Abbeele, University of Minnesota Press. Lyotard, Jean-Francois (1989) ‘Rewriting Modernity’ 54 Substance 8. Tom Mason (ed) (1989) Erle Stanley Gardner — Four Cases of Murder Starring Perry Mason, Malibu Graphics. Carrie Menkel-Meadow (2001) ‘Can They Do That? Legal Ethics in Popular Culture: Of Characters and Acts’ 48 UCLA Law Review 1305. Jim McGuigan (1996) Culture and the Public Sphere, Routledge. Alan McKee (2001) Australian Television: A Genealogy of Great Moments, Oxford University Press. Alan McKee (2004) An Introduction to the Public Sphere, Cambridge University Press. Joshua Meyrowitz (1985) No Sense of Place, Oxford University Press. 9/11 Commission Report 2004. The 9/11 Commission Report: The Final Report of the National Commission on Terrorist Attacks Upon the United States, WW Norton. Tim O’Sullivan, John Hartley, Danny Saunders, Martin Montgomery and John Fiske (1994) Key Concepts in Communication and Cultural Studies, Routledge. Paul R Pillar (2005) ‘Perceptions of Terrorism: Continuity and Change’, Law vs War: Competing Approaches to Fighting Terrorism: Conference Report, July, www.carlisle.army.mil/ssi. Steve Redhead (1995) Unpopular Cultures: The Birth of Law and Popular Culture, Manchester University Press. Richard Rorty (1989) Contingency, Irony and Solidarity, Cambridge University Press. Douglas Rushkoff (1994) Media Virus: Hidden Agendas in Popular Culture, Random House. Madan Sarup (1996) Identity, Culture and the Postmodern World, Edinburgh University Press. William H. Simon (2001) ‘Moral Pluck: Legal Ethics in Popular Culture’ 101 Columbia Law Review 2. Richard K Sherwin (2000) When Law Goes Pop: The Vanishing Line Between Law and Popular Culture, Chicago University Press. Richard K Sherwin (2001) ‘Nomos and the Law’ UCLA Law Review 1529. Richard Clarke Sterne (1998) ‘NYPD Blue’ in Robert M Jarvis and Paul R Joseph (eds), Prime Time Law, Carolina Academic Press. Jeffrey E Thomas (2001) ‘Legal Culture and The Practice: A Postmodern Depiction of the Rule of Law’ 48 UCLA Law Review 1495. Clive Thompson (2005) ‘Cruel Intentions: TV Torture Scenes are Ugly, Powerful, Exploitative — and a Mirror of Our National Debate’, New York Magazine, 7 February, www.newyorkmetro.com/nymetro/arts/tv/10966. BAINBRIDGE: LAWYERS, JUSTICE AND THE STATE 175 US Department of State (April 2004) Patterns of Global Terrorism 2003, www.globalsecurity.org/security/library/report/2004. Max Weber (1991) Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, trans Talcott Parsons, HarperCollins Academic. Films an d TV Series 24, FOX Network, 2001. Alias, ABC Network, 2001 Arrest and Trial, ABC Network (USA), 1963–64. The Bill, ITV1, 1983– Blue Heelers, Seven Network (Aust), 1994– Boney, Nine Network (Aust), 1972–73 Boston Legal, ABC Network (USA), 2004– Cagney and Lacey, CBS Network, 1982–88 Case for the Defence, Seven Network (Aust), 1974 The Closer, TNT, 2005– Columbo, NBC Network, 1971–77; ABC Network, 1989–93 Compulsion, Dir Richard Fleischer, 1959 Cracker, ITV1 Network, 1993–96 CSI: Crime Scene Investigation, CBS Network, 2000– Dirty Harry, Dir Don Siegel, 1971 Hawaii Five-O, CBS Network, 1968–80 Hill Street Blues, NBC Network, 1981–87 Homicide: Life on the Street, NBC Network, 1993–99 Inspector Morse, ITV1, 1987–2000 In the Name of the Father, Dir Jim Sheridan, 1993 Judge John Deed, ITV, 2004– LA Law, NBC Network, 1986–94 Law & Order, NBC Network, 1990– Law & Order: Criminal Intent, NBC Network, 2001– Law & Order: SVU (Special Victims Unit), NBC Network, 1999– Law & Order: Trial by Jury, NBC Network, 2005 Matlock, NBC Network, 1986–92; ABC Network (US), 1993–95 NYPD Blue, ABC Network, 1993–2005. Perry Mason — radio: 1943–55 — television (first run): CBS Network, 1957–66. — television (second run/different cast): CBS Network, 1973–74 Perry Mason Mysteries, The, NBC Network, 1985–97 The Practice, ABC Network (USA), 1997–2004. Rumpole of the Bailey, ITV1, 1978–92 The Shield, FX Network, 2002– Spooks, BBC, 2002– Stingers Undercover, Nine Network (Aust), 2000–04 The Sweeney, ITV1, 1975–78 176 GRIFFITH LAW REVIEW (2006) VOL 15 NO 1 To Kill a Mockingbird, Dir Robert Mulligan, 1962 Touch of Evil, Dir Orson Welles, 1958 (reconstructed 1998) Trial and Retribution, ITV1, 1997–2004 The Verdict, Dir Sidney Lumet, 1982 Without a Trace, CBS Network, 2002– work_eelccsi35jferd2ans6lkckuye ---- <35BCADB5B5BDC42E687770> I. II. ? III. 1. 2. IV. V. DOI : 10.21458/siuh.2016.8.1.005 사회적 노동과 정의 * 1) 서도식 서울시립대학교 철학과 이 논문에서 필자는 호네트의 인정이론에 의거하여 분배적 정의의 핵심 내용이 물질적 재화가 아닌 ‘인정’이라는 도덕적 자원의 재분배에 있음을 주장하고자 한다. 개인의 사회적 노동 활동의 목적은 자기보존 이 아니라 사회적 존재로서의 자신의 가치를 인정받는 데 있다. 왜냐 하면 개인의 사회적 노동의 성과는 타인과 사회 전체의 복지 증진에 기여하기 때문이다. 따라서 개인의 사회적 노동 분업 조직에의 참여와 그의 노동성과에 한 정당한 재분배는 호네트가 열거한 근 사회의 * 이 논문은 2009년도 정부재원(교육과학기술부 인문사회연구역량강화사업비)으로 한국연구재단 의 지원을 받아 연구되었음(KRF-2009-332-A00032). 130 8 1 3 인정 영역 중 하나인 사회적 가치평가 영역, 곧 연 성 확장의 도덕적 전제가 된다. 인정이론적 정의 모델은 이처럼 개인의 노동성과 에 기반한 업적 평가 외에도 사랑, 권리 동등 우 등을 정의의 원칙들 로 삼는 삼극적 모델이며, 사회는 이러한 다원적 정의 원칙들의 이행 으로 사회구성원 각자의 개성과 사회적 포용성의 증 를 뜻하는 도덕 적 진보를 달성한다. 주제어 : 인정, 사회적 노동, 정의, (재)분배, 호네트 work_eg76hyatyrfnjj2eomipsory3m ---- ewi003 57..75 Ex-Post Egalitarianism and Legal Justice Alon Harel Hebrew University of Jerusalem Zvi Safra Tel Aviv University Uzi Segal Boston College In any legal system, one finds numerous rules, practices, and constitutional pro- visions that are incompatible with utilitarian considerations. It is not merely util- itarianism that fails to explain a diverse range of rules and practices. Other theories that, like utilitarianism, involve ex ante considerations cannot explain them as well. There are two possible primary explanations for the prevalence of these nonutilitarian rules and practices: Kantian (deontological) explanations and a view we label ex post egalitarianism, which requires that the state decides on its action in an egalitarian manner ex post. Our approach allows for compar- isons among different societies by giving meaning to statements like ‘‘Society A is more egalitarian than society B.’’ Furthermore, we show that the more egal- itarian societies should also employ less extreme criminal law rules and should be more sensitive to various kinds of injustice, whether it is caused by individual wrongful behavior or by criminal law rules. 1. Introduction In any legal system, one finds numerous rules and practices as well as consti- tutional provisions that are incompatible with utilitarian considerations (i.e., with maximizing the sum of individual utilities). These rules and practices often grant benefits to an individual whose well-being is at risk; yet the costs of these benefits, in terms of utilities, to other individuals may outweigh these benefits. Thus, for instance, despite the persistent belief of economists that efficiency requires to impose the harshest possible sanctions, legal systems often impose light sanctions and consequently have to bear the high costs of increasing the probability of detection. It is not merely utilitarianism that fails to explain a diverse range of rules and practices. Other theories that, like utilitarianism, involve ex ante We thank Ariel Rubinstein for helpful discussions. Zvi Safra thanks the Israel Institute of Busi- ness research for its financial support. Uzi Segal thanks the National Science Foundation (grant 0111541) for financial aid. The Journal of Law, Economics, & Organization, Vol. 21, No. 1, doi:10.1093/jleo/ewi003 � The Author 2005. Published by Oxford University Press. All rights reserved. For Permissions, please email: journals.permissions@oupjournals.org JLEO, V21 N1 57 considerations cannot explain them as well. An ex ante analysis ranks distribu- tionsofexanteutilitiesbeforepeopleknowtheactualoutcometheyreceive. 1 Ex post analysis, on the other hand, relates to the final distribution of utilities. This analysis, too, is done before information concerning the distribution of final out- comesisrevealed,butrelatestotheevaluationofdistributionsoffinaloutcomes. There are two possible primary explanations for the prevalence of these non- utilitarian rules and practices: Kantian (deontological) explanations and a view we label ex post egalitarianism. Kantian explanations are based on the con- viction that there are nonconsequentialist obligations. The state is sometimes obliged to act or not to act in certain ways even if acting differently is con- ducive to utility, or to the ex ante interests of individuals. Typically those explanations rely on autonomy-based considerations and are based on the belief that respecting the dignity of individuals constrains the promotion of their well-being. For contemporary sophisticated deontological explanations of various rules and practices, see Kamm (1996:143–204). Ex post egalitarianism, on the other hand, requires that the State decide on its actioninanegalitarianmannerexpost.ItdiffersfromtheKantianapproachsince it is founded on a comparison between the well-being of the people who are affected by a certain rule and practice rather than presupposes the existence of moral constraints, which are independent of consequentialist considerations. It differs from utilitarianism since it is concerned with equality, and not only with the maximization of the sum of utilities. Finally, it differs from ex ante analysis, as itconsidersthe well-being of individuals after they have the knowledge of the prevailing social outcomes. The purpose of this article is to demonstrate that some legal rules and practices that are traditionally justified in terms of Kantian explanations can alternatively be explained in terms of ex post egalitarianism. Two impor- tant qualifications should be stated. First, we do not reject Kantian consider- ations. It is not claimed that the rules and practices examined here cannot be explained on the basis of Kantian considerations. Instead, we simply claim that they can also be explained in terms of ex post egalitarianism. Second, it is not claimed here that ex post egalitarianism is an absolute value, which overrides any conflicting values. The rules and practices examined here demonstrate that ex post egalitarianism competes with other considerations such as ex ante anal- ysis and utilitarian considerations. To demonstrate our approach, consider the issue of sentencing practices. As was argued by Becker (1968), sentencing practices pose a great challenge for the utilitarian approach: If criminals react to the expected sanction, then greater deterrence can be achieved by either increasing the probability of de- tection or by increasing the size of the sanction. However, increasing the prob- ability of detection is much more costly than increasing the size of the sanction. Hence the most efficient way to deter criminals is to impose the harshest 1. Note that when we use the term ‘‘ex ante’’ we do not discuss the extreme situation of ex ante decision process—the situation in which the decision is made behind the ‘‘veil of ignorance,’’ before the individual is even aware of his personal characteristics. 58 The Journal of Law, Economics, & Organization, V21 N1 sanction possible and to reduce accordingly the probability of detection. In reality, however, sanctions do not conform to Becker’s recommendations and they are usually proportional to the degree of culpability and wrongfulness of the crimes committed. Numerous explanations were provided to the puzzle raised by Becker. First, if criminals are risk averse, an increase in the sanction is not a costless transfer payment. Increasing the sanction and reducing the probability increases the risk faced by individuals. Second, the system proposed by Becker eliminates marginal deterrence—the incentive to substitute less for more serious crimes. We suggest below the following explanation. Sanctions generate inequality because those who are subjected to the sanctions are worse off relative to those who are not. The harsher the sanction is, the larger is the inequality between two classes of individuals, namely those offenders who are subjected to the sanction and nonoffenders who are subjected to the sanction by mistake, and offenders and nonoffenders who are not subjected to the sanction. Harsh sanctions are indeed, as Becker observed, required by consideration of aggre- gate utilities. Yet social interests in harsh sanctions must be balanced against social concerns for equality. Therefore it may well be the case that what dic- tates limits on the size of sanctions is ex post egalitarianism and not retributive justice considerations. Our approach allows for comparisons among different societies by giving meaning to statements like ‘‘Society A is more egalitarian than society B.’’ Furthermore, we show that the more egalitarian societies should also employ less extreme criminal law rules and should be more sensitive to various kinds of injustice, whether it is caused by individual wrongful behavior or by the society’s criminal law rules. As we elaborate in Section 8, such societies would use less harsh sentencing practices; furthermore, they would try to avoid wrong- ful convictions by raising the required burden of proof and, at the same time, they would try not to sacrifice minorities for the sake of the whole society. In Section 2 we present social policies and discuss the ex post and ex ante approaches. We define the notion of being an ex post egalitarian society and provide a way for comparing levels of egalitarianism among societies. In Sec- tion 3 we present our results, and we present our results and offer some appli- cations in Section 4. Formal analysis is deferred to the appendix. 2. Social Policies and Their Evaluation Consider a situation where individuals are facing some uncertainty regarding outcomes that are controlled by society, for example, road accidents or some health-related issues. There are many individuals and we assume that the risks they face are independent of each other. If society is sufficiently large, we can assume, for practical measures, that the proportion of those who receive a cer- tain outcome equals the probability of receiving this outcome. For example, if each member of society is facing an independent chance of 2% to fall victim to a car theft, then in a large society the probability that the true proportion of victims will differ from 2% by more than e is negligible. Social policies are Ex-Post Egalitarianism 59 often aimed at controlling these proportions, but they rarely try (or are even able) to determine the recipients of each outcome. For example, lower speed limits or wider road shoulders reduce the probability of fatal car accidents, but they do not tell who will be involved in accidents. There are two extreme ways in which society can view such issues: ex ante and ex post. Suppose that society is facing a choice between two economic policies. One implies an annual increase of 5% in everybody’s utility, the other provides each person with an independent risk, where there is a 50% chance of a 10% increase and a 50% chance of no change in utility. From an ex ante per- spective, both policies are equally attractive, as all expected utility maximizers are indifferent between the two. But the two policies may differ from an ex post perspective. The first implies a 5% increase in the utility of all. As individual risks are independent, the second policy implies (for a sufficiently large so- ciety) a 10% increase in the utility of half of the population and no change in the utility of the rest. If initially everybody’s utility is 100, now half of the population will have 110 and half will get only 100. Ex post, the two pol- icies are not the same and a nonutilitarian society may not be indifferent between them. Which is the correct analysis, the ex ante or the ex post? Consider another situation, where one unit of an indivisible good needs to be given to one of two individuals. Both receive utility one from receiving it and zero otherwise. All allocation procedures lead to an uneven allocation of ex post utility, one person receives one, the other zero. Diamond (1967:765) suggested randomization over the two individuals as a tool for improving social well-being, thus cre- ating ex ante egalitarianism. There is an extensive discussion in the literature about whether social welfare is really improved by such randomizations. Broome (1984a,b) argues in favor of ex post analysis, claiming that equality of expected utilities is not a real equality. Harsanyi (1977) also argues against attributing ex ante egalitarianism any significant value. Epstein and Segal (1992) focus attention on ex ante analysis, while Karni and Safra (2000) and, more explicitly, Ben Porath, Gilboa, and Schmeidler (1997) try to com- bine both ex post and ex ante consideration into one evaluation function. This article offers an ex post analysis, while assuming that society is not necessarily utilitarian (i.e., evaluations of social policies do not depend solely on the sum of individual utilities). We restrict attention to situations where each social policy leads to a known ex post distribution of utilities. As argued above, even though we cannot predict individual outcomes, we nevertheless know, for each policy, what proportion of the population will receive each possible utility level. We evaluate such distributions using a social welfare function W, which, not being utilitarian, is not necessarily linear. A utilitarian society is interested in maximizing the sum of individual util- ities and does not pay attention to the diversity of the distribution of utilities. Preferences for equality imply that society will be willing to reduce the av- erage utility in order to make the distribution more concentrated around its mean. Such concerns can be represented by quasi-concave functions, where the social evaluation of the average of two equally attractive distributions 60 The Journal of Law, Economics, & Organization, V21 N1 is better than both. 2 Such functions can be monotonic in individual utilities, but are also sensitive to utility differences between individuals, and admit some trade-off between the sum of utilities and their disparity. We now present an outline of our model; a more formal analysis appears in the appendix. Given two distributions of utility x and y, the mixture ax þ (1 � a)y gives each individual a times his allocation under x plus 1 � a times his allocation under y. For example, if x ¼ (3, 1) and y ¼ (1, 5), 1 2 x þ 1 2 y ¼ ð2; 3Þ. Our first assumption is that mixtures of equally attractive ex post utility distributions improve social welfare. Quasi-Concavity. Let x and y be two distributions of utility. If W(x) ¼ W(y), then for all a 2 (0, 1), W(ax þ (1 � a)y) c W(x). Strict quasi-concavity requires that for all x 6¼ y, W(x) ¼ W(y) implies W(ax þ (1 � a)y) > W(x).3 As mentioned above, we are interested here in utility distributions and do not care for the identity of the individual recipients of these utilities. Distri- bution x of utilities can therefore be represented as a cumulative distribution, where Fx(u) is the proportion of individuals whose utility given x does not exceed u. Two distributions that lead to the same cumulative distribution should therefore be equally attractive. Symmetry. If the two utility distributions x and y satisfy Fx ¼ Fy, then W(x) ¼ W(y). The major concept of the article is that of egalitarian social welfare functions: Definition 1. We say that a social welfare function is ex-post egalitarian if it is strictly quasi concave and symmetric. For a meaningful comparative statics analysis, we need to be able to com- pare different societies. For this, we will need the following concept: Definition 2. A social welfare function W# is more egalitarian than another social welfare function W if, whenever the society with the social welfare func- tion W is willing to sacrifice the difference between the averages of the two distributions in order to improve equality, so does the society with the social welfare function W#. 2. Recall that from an ex ante perspective, such functions imply preferences for randomizations. 3. Note the relation of this definition to Diamond’s (1967:765) argument in favor of ex ante evaluation—choosing the utility distribution x with probability p and y with probability 1 � p yields each individual expected utility that is equal to p times his utility under x plus 1 � p times his utility under y. Preferences for randomization imply quasi-concave preferences over social lotteries. Assuming that all individuals are expected utility maximizers, such preferences imply that the social welfare function is quasi-concave in ex ante utilities (Epstein and Segal, 1992). Ex-Post Egalitarianism 61 (see the Appendix for a more precise definition). Figure 1 depicts this concept for the case of two individuals. In this picture, W# is more egalitarian than W and distributions between x and E[x] (the average of the distribution x) display more equality. In the region between x and the main diagonal, the indifference curve through x of W# is lower than the corresponding indifference curve of W, hence W# is showing more egalitarianism than W. In the literature, considerations of equality that are based on cumulative dis- tributions lead to the concept of aversion to mean-preserving spreads. How- ever, by Dekel (1986), if W is symmetric and quasi-concave, then W must also represent such aversion, hence this concept of equality is related to the concept of quasi-concavity discussed above. 3. More Egalitarian Societies Suppose that society has control over a decision variable a 2 [0, 1] that leads to a utility distribution c(a). We assume that a > b implies that there is s such that the distribution of c(b) þ s is a mean-preserving spread of the distribution of c(a). In other words, as a moves from zero to one, c(a) is becoming more and more concentrated (even with respect to a changing average). The curve c(a) is called a track. The optimal value of a depends on social preferences, and our aim here is to compare these optimal values for societies with different degrees of ex post egalitarianism. The main result of the article is that the more egalitarian the society, the further it is willing to sacrifice average utility in order to reduce the variation of the optimal utility distribution. This result is stated in the following theorem. Figure 1. W# is more egalitarian than W. 62 The Journal of Law, Economics, & Organization, V21 N1 Theorem 1. If W# is more egalitarian than W, then along a track c where there is a substitution between average utility and spread, the optimal point for the more egalitarian function has a weakly lower sum of utilities and more concentration than the less egalitarian function. We present a formal statement of this theorem and provide a proof in the appendix. Moreover, we provide three conditions for a strict result (Theorem 2). Another result, implied by both theorems, is that an egalitarian society chooses a utility distribution that is more concentrated than the one chosen by a utilitarian society. This result is stated in the following corollary (and is proved in the appendix). Corollary 1. Let W be an ex-post egalitarian social welfare function and let c be a differentiable track. The optimal utility distribution of W is more con- centrated (and has a lower sum of utilities) than the optimal distribution of a utilitarian society. 4. Applications In this section we discuss some applications of our main result, namely, that a more egalitarian society will go further in the direction of reducing utility spread, even at the cost of total utility. 4.1 Victims of Crime versus Victims of the Criminal Law System Under the most fundamental principles of evidence law, facts constitutive of the defendant’s guilt have to be proven beyond a reasonable doubt. 4 This rule is perceived by practitioners as well as scholars to be grounded in justice-based considerations; it is often described as a right of defendants against the state. The rhetoric of rights and justice used in the justification of the strict standard of proof is often hostile to utilitarian calculations. This is no accident; utili- tarianism cannot in general justify the heightened burdens of proof associated with this principle. To see it, assume that a legal system can adopt either a strict or a lenient rule of proof. Under the strict rule, guilt has to be proven beyond a reasonable doubt. Under the lenient rule, guilt has to be proven in a ‘‘satisfactory man- ner.’’ Each one of these alternative rules involves costs and benefits, and there 4. This is an old principle of common law. An important articulation of it can be found in the English landmark case of Woolmington v. DPP [1935] A.C. 462. The court stated there unambig- uously that ‘‘No matter what the charge or where the trial, the principle that the prosecution must prove the guilt of the prisoner is part of the Common Law of England and no attempt to whittle it down can be entertained’’ (see Woolmington v. DPP [1935] A.C. 481). In the United States the same principle is regarded as required by the due process clause. The Supreme Court stated that this clause ‘‘protects the accused against conviction except upon proof beyond reasonable doubt of every fact necessary to constitute the crime with which he is charged.’’ See In Winship, 397 U.S. 358, 364 (1970). The rule however had much longer and deeper roots which can be traced to Roman law (Williams, 1963:186–190). Ex-Post Egalitarianism 63 is some trade-off between convicting the innocent and acquitting the guilty (Williams, 1963:188, Wertheimer, 1977:51–52). It is reasonable to believe that a legal system that adopts the lenient rule fulfills better its task of protecting its citizens from crime than a system that adopts the strict rule and the costs of the strict principle in terms of deterrence may outweigh the benefits the strict principle provides to the innocent people who are better protected under it from wrongful conviction. In that case, util- itarianism dictates a rejection of the strict rule. In their efforts to justify the strict rule, utilitarians often develop justifica- tions that depend on some restrictive assumptions. Bentham (1825:197), for example, supported the claim that there ought to be a presumption in favor of the accused, writing: ‘‘Generally speaking, a too easy acquittal excites regret and uneasiness only among men of reflection; while the condemnation of an accused, who turns out to have been innocent, spreads general dismay; all se- curity appears to be destroyed; no defence can any longer be found, when even innocence is insufficient.’’ Yet moral theorists usually reject utilitarian justi- fications for the principle that guilt should be proven beyond a reasonable doubt (Dworkin, 1986:72,81–84). Some of their arguments rely on the intu- ition that wrongful conviction seems to be a direct interference in the lives of an innocent person. In contrast, the failure to prevent a crime is merely an omission on the part of the state. Expostegalitarianismisanin-betweenapproach.LikeBenthamandlikeutil- itarianism, it does not ignore the individual costs and benefits of different bur- dens of proof. However, it also considers social norms and notions of justice, whicharerepresentedbythequasi-concavityofthesocialwelfarefunction.Such functions pay more attention to the well-being of those members of society who areworseoffcomparedtotherest.Toillustrate,considerthefollowingstructure. Society is composed of innocents and criminals. Innocent people face the risk of wrong conviction and the risk of criminal victimhood. Criminals may or may not be caught and convicted (for simplicity, we ignore minor groups such as criminals who are not convicted but are victims of crime). For a given level of burden of proof a, we get an ex post utility distribution of the form cðaÞ ¼ ðui; piÞ5i¼1; where u1 is the utility of convicted innocents, u2 is the utility of convicted criminals, u3 is the utility of innocent victims of crime, u4 is the utility of innocents, and u5 is the utility of the unconvicted criminals. We as- sume that crime benefits the criminal, that punishment is more severe than the consequences of the criminal act, and that wrongful conviction is worse than just conviction to the bearer of the punishment. Therefore we assume u1 < . . . < u5 (see distribution s1 —the continuous line—in Figure 2). As explained in Section 2, pi is the proportion in the population of those who receive utility ui (and is also the probability of getting this utility level). Society now raises the burden of proof while simultaneously raising the probability of detection so that the level of crime in society remains untouched. The reason for this simultaneous act is the desire that the cost of the increase in crime level be shared by the whole society and not only by the additional vic- tims. Criminals are interested in the probability of being punished, which is the 64 The Journal of Law, Economics, & Organization, V21 N1 product of the probability of detection and the conditional probability of con- viction given detection. As crime does not change, this combined probability too does not change. Moreover, assuming one crime per criminal, the number of criminals is unchanged. Therefore the number of those who receive utility levels u2 and u5 is unchanged. Also, the size of the u3 part of society is not changed—these being the people who suffer from crime. Obviously the combination of higher burden of proof and higher rate of de- tection that does not change the crime rate will reduce the number of convicted innocents, hence the size of the u1 level will go down, while the size of the u4 group will increase. Better detection is of course not cost free. Suppose that society finances the cost by taxing those who are not convicted and did not suffer from crime, that is, groups 4 and 5. 5 The new distribution is depicted by curve s2 (the dotted line). Obviously the second distribution intersects the first one only once, and from below. If the first distribution is optimal, then the new distribution must have a lower expected value, otherwise, as it is less spread than before, a higher expectation would have prevented distribution s1 from being optimal, even for a utilitarian society, and certainly for an egalitarian one. We strengthen this statement by assuming that the expected value is actually monotonically decreasing as we move from the first to the second distribution. The conditions of Theorem 1 are thus satisfied (observe that the set of dis- tributions society can choose from is a track) (section 3). Even when the second distribution is shifted to the right by the whole increased cost of detection, there will be only one crossing point, and the expected value of the shifted distribution will be more than the expected value of distribution s1 ). We there- fore find out that the more egalitarian society will seek a higher level of burden of proof. Our analysis does not imply that the optimal social policy is to set the burden of proof at its highest possible level (‘‘beyond any reasonable doubt’’). We Figure 2. Burden of proof. 5. Arguably, one should tax group 3 as well (recall that groups 1 and 2 cannot be taxed, as they are serving jail terms). However, we will ignore this tax in order to satisfy the conditions of Theorem 1. For infinitesimal changes this tax is indeed negligible, as the number of those who suffer from (serious) crime is small compared to the number of those who are not affected by it, and the tax is small compared to the sanction against criminals. Ex-Post Egalitarianism 65 recognize the validity of two claims on the social ruling. The obligation to increase social well-being, but also the obligation to promote equality. Unlike utilitarianism, and unlike some of the above justifications for the strict rule, we refuse to give one claim lexicographic dominance over the other. Ex post egal- itarian social welfare functions do indeed take both factors into consideration. 4.2 Torture and Other Forms of Cruel Punishment One of the most puzzling concerns of the legal economist is the ceiling on the size of the criminal sanction. Since Becker (1968), legal economists tried to explain the reasons for the widely held intuition that the criminal law system should not impose the maximally possible sanctions. Becker’s argument is simple and yet compelling. An expected punishment of $1000 can be imposed by different combinations of fines and probabilities of apprehension. If the costs of collecting fines are assumed to be zero, regard- less of the size of the fine, but the costs of apprehending and convicting crim- inals rise with the probability of apprehension, 6 then the most efficient combination is a probability close to zero and a fine arbitrarily close to infinity (see Becker, 1968; see also Posner, 2003:219–227). Under this argument, the only optimal sanction for every crime is the most extreme—possibly torture and death. Such a sanction enables one to obtain that even very low probability of apprehension and conviction would be sufficient to guarantee a sufficiently large expected sanction. Yet our legal system does not conform to the Becker model. Instead, our system imposes a ceiling on criminal sanctions. Torture is prohibited altogether in modern legal systems and most modern legal systems do not impose capital punishment. There are several primary explanations for the ceilings on criminal sanc- tions. Some legal economists dispute some of the presuppositions of Becker’s analysis. They point out that criminals may be risk averse or risk preferring, and if criminals are not risk neutral, Becker’s analysis does not yield the same outcome (Polinsky and Shavell, 1979). Moreover, economists point out the importance of marginal deterrence, that is, the incentive to substitute less for more serious crimes as a reason for differentiating between the sanctions imposed for different crimes (Shavell, 1983:1245–1246; Posner, 2003:222). Traditional criminal law provides, Kantian justification to the ceiling on sanc- tions. The wrongfulness and the culpability of criminals dictate what they de- serve and criminal law should not impose any sanctions that exceed what is being deserved. For a use of this Kantian insight, see Nozick, (1981/2000:363– 397) and Fletcher (2000:454–491). Ex post egalitarian considerations could explain the very same phenome- non. Criminal sanctions yield benefits that are provided to the public at large at the cost of the particular individual upon whom they are imposed. The im- position of criminal sanctions contributes to the well-being of others by 6. These costs are increasing with the probability because higher probabilities imply more po- lice, prosecutors, judges, defense attorneys, etc. 66 The Journal of Law, Economics, & Organization, V21 N1 producing deterrence. Yet, if too large sanctions are imposed on a small group of individuals, the disparity between the well-being of those who bear the costs of deterrence and those who benefit from it is too large. The ceiling on the criminal sanction is aimed at constraining this disparity. As before, society is composed of innocents and criminals. The first group consists of victims of crime (with the utility u2) and of nonvictims (with the utility u3), while the second group consists of those who are punished (u1) and of those who are not (u4). 7 Here too we assume that crime benefits the criminals and that punishment is more severe than the consequences of the criminal act. Therefore we assume u1 < . . . < u4, see distribution s1 in Figure 3. Society now reduces the severity of punishment while simultaneously rais- ing the probability of detection so that the number of convicted criminals is not higher than before. It follows that the number of criminals is thus decreasing (as before, we assume one crime and one victim per criminal). This, of course, is not cost free (otherwise, society would not have been at an optimal point), and we assume, as before, that the financial burden falls on the shoulders of those who are not convicted and did not suffer from crime (see footnote 5). The new distribution is depicted by curve s2. In this distribution, the utility of convicted criminals is higher than before (as the punishment is less severe), and there are not more of them than before. The utility of unconvicted crim- inals is less than before (they have to pay for better detection), and since the overall crime rate is down and the probability of detection is higher, the size of this group diminishes. As there are fewer crimes, there are fewer victims of crime, but their utility is the same as before. Finally, less crime means more people who are neither criminals nor victims (the old u3 group), but since they Figure 3. Cruel punishment. 7. We ignore here the possible existence of innocent people who are wrongly convicted. For the sake of simplicity, we assume that all innocent people share the same utility. Relaxing this assump- tion would not affect the outcome of our analysis. For example, introducing an additional group of typical and nonactive potential criminals whose social state is inferior to innocent non-victims and superior to innocent victims would create a new utility level u# between u2 and u3. Since it is reasonable to assume that this group is small and less wealthy, and hence only little taxes are imposed on it, our analysis holds for this case as well. Ex-Post Egalitarianism 67 have to pay for better detection, their utility goes down. Obviously the new distribution intersects the first one only once, and from below. If the first distribution is optimal, then the new distribution must have a lower expected value, otherwise, as it is less spread than before, a higher expectation would have prevented distribution s1 from being optimal even for a utilitarian society. We thus assume that the expected value is monotonically decreasing as we move from the first to the second distribution. It is reasonable to assume that crime benefits criminals less than the harm it imposes on its victims (otherwise it would have been socially optimal to have more crime, at least for a utilitarian society). In other words, u4 � u3 < u3 � u2. Moreover, since the number of convicted criminals is reduced, the change in the number of victims must be higher than the change in the number of un- punished criminals. In other words, when the new distribution s1 is shifted to the right by the full amount of the increased cost of detection, its expected value will be higher than the original distribution, hence the social choice set is a track. The conditions of Theorem 1 are thus satisfied, and we therefore find out that the more egalitarian society will seek less severe punishment than the less egalitarian one. 4.3 Sacrificing Some for the Rest The problem of whether or not society should sacrifice some (hopefully few) individuals to save the rest is at least 2500 years old. In Iphigeneia at Aulis, Euripides describes the attempted sacrifice of Iphigeneia to appease Artemis’ wrath, thus obtaining fair wind to carry the Greek navy out of the bay of Aulis to sail for Troy (Hornblower and Spaworth, 1996:765). Similarly the rabbin- ical law deals with the situation of a group of people who are surrounded by enemies and are asked to surrender one of them to be killed. The law is that they should all be killed, but should not do it, unless the enemy specified the one they wanted (Tosefta, 1977:20). In both sources there is an unambiguous reluctance to accept the idea that social goals may be achieved by sharply re- ducing the well-being of some members of society. Figure 4. Sacrificing some for the rest. 68 The Journal of Law, Economics, & Organization, V21 N1 In this subsection we discuss a similar problem, where society can reduce the utility of a minority to improve the position of the majority. We assume a homogeneous society, where initially everyone has utility level u1. By re- ducing the utility of some members of society it is possible to increase the utility of the rest—two such possibilities are depicted in Figure 4 (distributions s2 and s3 distribution s1 represents the fully egalitarian situation). Such redis- tributions of utility can be obtained, for example, by a military draft, jury duty, and other such obligations. If the expected value of the third distribution is less than that of the second one, then there is no point in switching from s2 to s3 even in a utilitarian society. We therefore assume that the expected value in monotonically decreasing as society is moving from distribution s3 to s2. Shifting distribution s3 to the left to get the same expected value as that of distribution s2 will maintain the single, fewer crossing property of the two distributions, hence Theorem 1 may be applied. We obtain that the more egalitarian society will opt for fewer benefits for the privileged at the cost of the underprivileged. We would like to emphasize that our analysis does not imply that society should not recruit only part of the citizenry, as it may well be that the fully egalitarian distribution is suboptimal, for example, when a relatively modest reduction in utility for a small number of individuals can significantly increase the utility of the rest. But the ex post egalitarian society is certainly more sen- sitive than the utilitarian society to issues of utility distribution, and will there- fore ask for greater benefits for the privileged than the utilitarian society before it agrees to further sacrifices by the underprivileged. 5. Conclusion Our most fundamental rules and practices constrain the pursuit of maximiza- tion of utility. It is often natural to explain these constraints as grounded in deontological considerations founded on principles of dignity and inviolability of persons. This indeed has been the explanation traditionally given to many of the rules and principles constraining the pursuit of utility. This article provides an additional explanation—one that relies on principles of ex post egalitarianism. More specifically, it is argued that ex post egalitar- ianism can explain a broad array of rules and practices, including the require- ment that guilt be proven beyond reasonable doubt, the prohibition on torture and cruel and unjust punishment, and the prohibition of sacrificing some for the sake of saving others. These rules and practices constrain the pursuit of utility. At the same time, they reallocate utility in a fashion that promotes ex post egal- itarianism. More specifically, they reduce the costs which otherwise would be imposed on people whose well-being turns out ex post to be lower at the expense of those whose well-being turns out ex post to be higher. Unlike ex ante egalitarianism, which is often achieved through randomiza- tions over social members, ex post egalitarianism involves a real transfer of goods from some individuals to others. It is therefore important that these goods be divisible, as indeed are the goods in all of our examples. Ex-Post Egalitarianism 69 6. Appendix Let X be the set of real bounded random variables on the probability space (S, R, P), and let Fx denote the cumulative distribution function of x 2 X, where X is the set of all utility distributions. Generic elements of X are denoted x, y, z, while degenerate random variables are denoted r, s, t. Scalars are denoted a, b, c. A preference relation c is a binary relation on X that is complete, transitive, continuous, 8 and monotone with respect to the relation of first-order stochastic dominance (as usual, ; denotes indifference and _ denotes strict preference). The preference relation c is symmetric if for all x; y 2 X; Fx ¼ Fy 0 x ; y: It is quasi-concave if for all x; y 2 X; x ; y 0 "a 2 ð0; 1Þ; ax þ ð1 � aÞy c x (strict quasi-concavity is defined with strict preferences). Note that quasi concavity is defined with respect to outcomes, and not with respect to probabilities. By construction, quasi-concavity implies preferences for av- eraging, hence it is related to equity-seeking behavior. Let U denote the set of all symmetric and quasi-concave preference relations on X. The social welfare functions W and W# used in this article represent preferences in U. Example 1. Consider the set L � U of preference relations that satisfy positive linearity: for all a > 0 and for all r 2 v x c y5ax þ r c ay þ r Let c 2 L and pick a non-degenerate utility distribution x. The preference relation c can be fully reconstructed from the set fy 2 v : y ; x and E½y� ¼ E½x�g and from the unique degenerate distribution a that satisfy a ; x. The set L was characterized in Safra and Segal (1998). Definition 3. Let c, c# 2 U. The preference relation c# is more egali- tarian than c if for all x 2 v fy 2 v : y c x and E½y�E½x�g � fy 2 v : y#x and E½y�E½x�g The preference relation c# is strictly more egalitarian than c if these inclu- sions are strict for all non-degenerate x. Note that the relation ‘‘more egalitarian than’’ is a partial order on the set of preference relations U. Fact 1. Assume c# is more egalitarian than c and that they are both strictly quasi-concave. Then, for all x 2 X; fy 2 X : y ; #x and E½y� ¼ E½x�g ¼ fy 2 X : y ; x and E½y� ¼ E½x�g: That is, both induce the same preferences over subspaces in which the expected values are fixed. 8. We use the topology of weak convergence with the Lévy metric on it. This metric is defined by d(F, G) ¼ inffe > 0: For all x, G(x – e) – e � F(x) � G(x þ e) þ eg; see Huber (1977). 70 The Journal of Law, Economics, & Organization, V21 N1 Proof. Let x 2 X and denote Ix ¼ fy 2 X : y ; x and E½y� ¼ E½x�g and I#x ¼ fy 2 X : y ; #x and E½y� ¼ E½x�g: First consider y 2 Ix. By definition, y c# x. If y c# x, then x 2 fz 2 X : z c y and E½z� � E½y�gnfz 2 X : z c #y and E½z� � E½y�g; a contradiction to the assumption that c# is more egalitarian than c. Next consider y 2 I#x\Ix and let a denote the degenerate utility distribution in which all utilities are equal to E[x]. By strict quasi-concavity, a _ x and a _ y. If x _ y, then, by continuity, there exist k 2 (0, 1), such that z ¼ ky þ (1 � k)a satisfies z ; x. Since z 2 Ix, it follows by the above argument that z 2 I#x, hence z ; #y; a contradiction to the strict quasi-concavity of c#. Since y;Ix, it must be the case that y _ x. By the strict quasi-concavity of c# and the continuity of c, there exists z satisfying E[z] ¼ E[x], x _#z, and z _ x. Hence, z 2 fy 2 X : y c x and E½y� � E½x�gnfy 2 X : y c #x and E½y� � E½x�g; a contradiction to the assumption that c# is more egalitarian than c. n Let x8y denote that Fy is a mean-preserving spread of Fx while Fx 6¼ Fy. The following fact shows that if c# is (strictly) more egalitarian than c, then, whenever the addition of r > 0 suffices to compensate the preference relation c# for the lack of equity manifested by y, then r (more than) suffices for the preference relation c. This result demonstrates the close connection between our definition and the strong measure of risk aversion suggested by Ross (1981). Note that the analysis of Ross is restricted to a subset of preferences in U—preferences that correspond to expected utility preferences in the liter- ature on risk. Fact 2. If c# is more egalitarian than c, then, for all x; y; r 2 X such that x 8 y, y þ r c #x 0 y þ r c x: Similarly, if c# is strictly more equitable than c, then y þ r c #x 0 y þ r_x: Proof. Let x, y, and r satisfy x8y, y þ r c#x, and x _ y þ r. By mono- tonicity, there exists z ¼ y þ r# (r# > r) satisfying z ; x and z ;#x þ r$ _# x (r$ > 0). Hence x belongs to fw 2 X : w c z and E½w� � E½z�g; while it does not belong to fw 2 X : wc#z and E½w� � E½z�g; a contradiction to the assumption that c# is more egalitarian than c. n Definition 4. A track is a function c : [0,1] / v such that a > b 0 cðaÞ 8 cðbÞ þ s for some s 2 v.9 9. s is a function of a and b. Ex-Post Egalitarianism 71 Note that s can be either a positive or a nonpositive distribution. Also note that if c(a) is a degenerate distribution, than a¼1. Otherwise, if c(a) is a mean- preserving spread of c(1) þ s, then c(a)¼ c(1) þ s, while the definition of 8requires the two to be different from each other. Theorem 1. Let c, c# 2 U and assume that c# is more egalitarian than c. Let c be a track and let c (a) and c (a#) be the unique optimal distributions of c and c# along c, respectively. Then a# � a. Proof. Suppose that a > a# and let s satisfy c(a)8c(a#) þ s. Consider first the case s c 0. The quasi-concavity of c# implies that c(a)c#c(a#) þ s. By monotonicity, c(a#) þ s#c(a#), hence c(a)c#c(a#), a violation of the assump- tion that a# is the unique optimal point of c# along c. Suppose now that s < 0. By assumption, c(a#) c#c(a). Since c# is more egalitarian than c, it follows Fact 2 and from the fact that c(a)8c(a#) þ s that cða#Þ ¼ ½cða#Þ þ s� þ ð�sÞ_#cðaÞ 0 cða#Þ_cðaÞ: A contradiction to the assumption that a is the unique optimal point of c alongc. It thus follows that a# c a. n Figure 5. Proof of Theorem 2. 72 The Journal of Law, Economics, & Organization, V21 N1 Next we want to establish conditions under which a# is strictly greater than a. Define the positive tangent c#þ(a) to satisfy c#þðaÞ ¼ lim anYa ¼ cðanÞ � cðaÞkcðanÞ � cðaÞk ; where k�k is with respect to the Lévy metric (see footnote 8). Definition 5. The track c : [0,1] / v is equitably-differentiable if for all a the tangent c#þðaÞ is well defined and there exists �c > 0 such that for all 0 < c < �c; cðaÞ þ cc#þðaÞ8cðaÞ þ s for some s ¼ s (a, c) 2 v. The ray cðaÞ þ cc#þðaÞ is the linear continuation of the curve c from the point c(a). The condition of the last display equation says that small movements in this direction increase the level of equity. (Recall that all preferences in U are quasi-concave.) Definition 6. The preference relation c 2 U is smooth is for all non- degenerate x 2 v there exists a unique linear function gx : v / < such that y ; x implies gx(y) � gx(x), and moreover, gx is continuous in x. Since a hyperplane in X is an indifference set of a linear function, it follows that if a preference relation c 2 U is smooth, then for all x 2 X there is a unique hyperplane Hx supporting the indifference set at that point. Note that Fréchet differentiability may not imply this property (Machina, 2001; Safra and Segal, 2001). Let c, c# 2 U be strictly quasi-concave and smooth and assume that c# is strictly more egalitarian than c. Let Hx (similarly H#x) be the supporting hyperplane to the indifference set of c(c#) through the nondegenerate dis- tribution x. Let D denote the line generated by all degenerate distributions, D ¼ fr : r 2 Xg; and consider the two-dimensional plane T ¼ SpanfD, xg. By monotonicity, D is not contained in Hx, hence Hx \ T is a line. By monotonicity and quasi-concavity there exists t satisfying ftg ¼ (Hx \ T) \ D and, by symmetry and strict quasi-concavity, t < E[x] (see Figure 5). By construction, Hx \ T ¼ fxg þ Spanfx � tg. Let Jx (J#x) be the indifference curves of c (c#) in T through x. Let Gx ¼ fy 2 X : E½y� ¼ E½x�g: Clearly, Hx ¼ SpanfHx \ Gx, x � tg and, by Fact 1, H#x \ Gx ¼ Hx \ Gx. By definition, the curves Jx and J#x intersect each other at x such that the following holds: Jx lies above J#x between x and D and Jx lies below J#x other- wise. This, however, is not sufficient to imply that x þ (x – t) does not belong to H#x. To have this, we assume the following generic assumption: ð*ÞFor all nondegenerate x; HðxÞ 6¼ H#ðxÞ: Ex-Post Egalitarianism 73 Note that the set of points fx : Hx \ T ¼ H#x \ Tg is the complement of an open and dense set (by comparability, Hx \ T ¼ H#x \ T iff Hx ¼ H#x; by smoothness, the set of points where Hx 6¼ H#x is open; and the fact that c# is more strictly equitable than c implies that there is no open set on which Hx ¼ H#x). Theorem 2. Let c, c# 2 U be strictly quasi concave and smooth. Assume that c# is strictly more egalitarian than c, and that condition (*) is satisfied. Let c be an equitably-differentiable track and let c(a) and c(a#) be the unique optimal points of c and c# along c, respectively. If a < 1, the a# > a. Proof. Since a < 1, c(a) must be a non-degenerate distribution (see the discussion after Definition 2 above). By Theorem 1, it is sufficient to show that a# 6¼ a. Consider the tangent c#þ(a). By the optimality of x, x þ c#þ(a) 2 Hx. There- fore x þ c#þ(a) ¼ z þ d(x � t) for some d, where z 2 Hx \ Gx ( ¼ H#x \ Gx). We show that x þ c#þ(a) does not belong to Hx \ Gx. Assume the contrary. Since c is equitably differentiable, it follows that for sufficiently small c > 0, c(a) þ cc#þ(a)8c(a) (note that the s in the definition of an equitably differentiable track satisfies s ¼ 0). The smoothness of c implies that for sufficiently small c > 0, c(a þ c) c c(a); a contradiction. Therefore d 6¼ 0. It follows by condition (*) that x þ (x � t) does not belong to H#x. Now d 6¼ 0 implies that x þ c#þ(a) does not belong to H#x. Therefore the optimality of c(a#) for c# shows that c(a#) 6¼ x and a# 6¼ a. n Corollary 2. Let c, c# 2 U such that c# is strictly quasi concave and smooth and c is a utilitarian preference relation. Let c be an equitably- differentiable track and let c(a) and c(a#) be the unique optimal points of c and c#, respectively. If a < 1, then a# > a. Proof. We will use the notations of the previous proof. By Theorem 1, a# c a. The condition that c is a utilitarian preference relation implies that the supporting hyper plane to the indifference set of c through the nondegenerate distribution x satisfies Hx ¼ Gx (note that t ¼ E[x]) and the tangent vector x þ c#þ(a) belongs to Hx \ Gx. As in the former proof, the facts that c is equitable- differentiable and that c# is smooth, symmetric, and strictly quasi-concave imply that for sufficiently small c > 0, c(a þ c) c#c(a), hence a# > a. References Becker, G.S. 1968. ‘‘Crime and Punishment: An Economic Approach,’’ 76 Journal of Political Economy 169–217. Ben Porath, E., I. Gilboa, and D. Schmeidler. 1997. ‘‘On the Measurement of Inequality Under Uncertainty,’’ 75 Journal of Economic Theory 194–204. Bentham, J. 1825. A Treatise on Judicial Evidence. London: Paget. Broome, J. 1984a. ‘‘Uncertainty and Fairness,’’ 94 Economic Journal 624–32. ———. 1984b. ‘‘Selecting People Randomly,’’ 95 Ethics 38–55. Dekel, E. 1989. ‘‘Asset Demand Without the Independence Axiom,’’ 57 Econometrica 163–69. Diamond, P.A. 1967. ‘‘Cardinal Welfare, Individualistic Ethics, and Interpersonal Comparison of Utility: Comment,’’ 75 Journal of Political Economy 765–66. 74 The Journal of Law, Economics, & Organization, V21 N1 Dworkin, R. 1986. ‘‘Principle, Policy, Procedure,’’ in R. Dworkin: A Matter of Principle. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Epstein, L.G., and U. Segal. 1992. ‘‘Quadratic Social Welfare Functions,’’ 100 Journal of Political Economy 691–712. Fletcher, G. 2000. Rethinking Criminal Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Harsanyi, J.C. 1977. Rational Behavior and Bargaining Equilibrium in Games and Social Situa- tions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Hornblower, S., and A. Spaworth. 1996. The Oxford Classical Dictionary. Oxford: Oxford Uni- versity Press. Huber, P.J. 1977. Robust Statistics Procedures. Society for Industrial and Applied Mathematics. Kamm, F.M. 1996: Morality, Mortality, vol. II. New York: Oxford University Press. Karni, E., and Z. Safra. 2002. ‘‘Individual Sense of Justice: A Utility Representation,’’ 70 Econ- ometrica 263–84. Machina, M. 2001. ‘‘Payoff Kinks in Preferences Over Lotteries,’’ 23 Journal of Risk and Un- certainty 207–60. Myerson, R. 1981. ‘‘Utilitarianism, Egalitarianism and the Timing Effect in Social Choice Prob- lems,’’ 49 Econometrica 883–97. Nozick, R. 1981. Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Polinsky, M., and S. Shavell. 1979. ‘‘The Optimal Tradeoff Between the Probability and Magni- tude of Fines,’’ 69 American Economic Review 880–91. Posner, R. 2003. Economic Analysis of Law, 6th ed. New York. Aspen Law & Business. Roemer, J.E. 1996. Theories of Distributive Justice. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press. Ross, S.A. 1981. ‘‘Some Stronger Measures of Risk Aversion in the Small and in the Large with Applications,’’ 49 Econometrica 621–38. Safra, Z., and U. Segal. 1998. ‘‘Constant Risk Aversion,’’ 83 Jornal of Economic Theory 19–42. ———. 2002. ‘‘On the Ecomomic Meaning of Machina’s Fréchet Differentiability Assumption,’’ 104 Journal of Economic Theory 450–61. Shavell, S. 1985. ‘‘Criminal Law and the Optimal Use of Nonmonetary Sanctions as a Deterrent,’’ 85 Columbia Law Review 1232–62. Tosefta, 1977. Translated by J. Neusner. New York: Ktav. Wertheimer, A. 1977. ‘‘Punishing the Innocent Unintentionally,’’ 20 Inquiry 45. Williams, G. 1963. The Proof of Guilt: A Study of the English Criminal Trial, 3rd ed. London: Stevens. Ex-Post Egalitarianism 75 work_ehotxdwno5fdjhsusmfrxvf6ym ---- Philosophica 52 (1993, 2) pp. 75-103 SOCIAL JUSTICE AND INDIVIDUAL ETHICS· Philippe Van Parijs It happened to me when bargaining over the price of a hammock on a Mexican beach, when checking my purse in my back pocket on a packed Italian bus and when running into a legless beggar on a Russian souvenir market. It happens to me every year when wondering whether I should report on my tax form the fees or royalties I earned abroad. It happens to me every week when chucking outunread yet another leaflet from yet another charity that caught my name on its mailing list. And it happens to me nearly every day when hearing one of my children ask for more, or nicer, or bigger than what (s)he has already been spoiled with. On all these occasions - and on countless others -, I hit upon the nagging, discomforting question of what, if anything, my professed beliefs about social justice entail for my personal conduct, of what constraints, if any, a person's conception of justice imposes on her personal ethics!, or of what it means to be ethically consistent across the political/individual boundary. In particular - I cannot help asking -, if one is committed - as I am - to some broadly "Rawlsian" conception of justice, is one not also necessarily committed to a broadly "Christian" personal ethics?2 More explicitly, if one believes that justice requires the maximinning of mate- rial conditions - however the latter are precisely defined, and possibly subject to the respect of self-ownership, fundamental liberties, or the like -, should one not use one's time and resources as well as one can in order to assist the poorest, the most vulnerable - subject, presumably, to not making oneself worse off than them in the process and also pos- sibly, again, to the respect of other people's fundamental liberties, self- ownership and the like? Or more succinct! y, does it make ethical sense to advocate maximin institutions while recoiling from maximin conduct? 76 PHILIPPE VAN PARIJS Can one consistently be a "Rawlsian" without also being a "Christian"? 1. Managerial dilemmas, utilitarian distinctions Those anxious to find reasons to support what I shall call the dichotomic view, i.e. a positive answer to this last question, may first appeal to the following sort of example, which suggests that if you are a Rawlsian, consistency does not only allow you not to be a Christian, but prevents you from being one. Consider the choice of a manager committed to a maximin conception of justice who has to sack one of her workers. Does her commitment to (a lexical version ot) maximin demand that she should sack, not her worst worker, for whom it is likely to be most difficult to find another job, but her best worker, for whom this is likely to be easiest? Or suppose she has to hire someone. Should she seek out the person who most needs the job and is likely to be the least employable, the least productive among the applicants? Surely, this inference from maximin at the macro-level to maximin at the micro-level is spurious, as the latter, when consistently practiced, is bound to undermine the former, by gravely impairing the economy's performance, and hence making the best material condition that can sustainably be granted to the worst off considerably worse than is necessary. Far from implying a maximin personal ethics, commitment to a maximin conception of social justice seems to rule it out. But one should not make too much of this sort of example. For all it does, in the present context, is warn against a naive interpretation of the policy implications of the maximin at both the political and the per- sonal level. If one can sufficiently trust the efficiency of the institutional framework, and especially of its redistributive component, it will general- ly be best, for the sake of the worst off in our society, if managers do not try, when hiring or firing, when buying or selling, and in any other professional circumstances, to benefit the worst off, but maximize instead their firms' expected profits. However, this does not exemplify a discrep- ancy between social justice and individual ethics. It simply reflects the fact that the behavioural rule which maximin-designed institutions should impose or which maximin-minded agents should follow in some specific role, need not be maximin itself. 3 In the same spirit, rule utilitarians are likely to recommend that judges take decisions in line with their convic- SOCIAL JUSTICE AND INDIVIDUAL ETHICS 77 tions about who is guilty, rather than on the basis of their conjectures about which decision would be best for aggregate welfare. What is shown by examples of this sort is not that maximin social justice rules out max- imin personal conduct, but that neither must be understood and imple- mented in too simplistic a fashion. Does the utilitarian tradition not provide a second, and more rele- vant, type of support to those who would like to cut the link from max- imin justice to maximin conduct? True, if you believe that some version of utilitarianism provides the correct answer to the question of how each individual ought to behave, then it is hard to see how you could deny that the same version of utilitarianism provides the criterion in terms of which alternative institutional setups are to be evaluated. If your individual ethics is utilitarian, how could your conception of justice be anything else? But it does not follow that it is impossible to be utilitarian on the social level - a just social framework is one that maximizes expected aggregate welfare -, while having, for example, a hedonistic life ideal. Indeed, this possibility seems emphatically asserted when utilitarians stress that the content of each person's welfare is "liberally" left entirely open or, even more perhaps, when they want to cleanse people's prefe- rences of any "other-regarding" element the latter may contain, in order to avoid the inappropriate discounting or multiple counting of some people's preferences.3 On reflection, however, all this can be reconciled with the claim that if we must try to maximize aggregate welfare in the choice of institutions, then we must also do so in our personal conduct. For suppose all mem- bers of society are committed utilitarians at both the individual and the social level. If utilitarianism, at both levels, is to avoid unwelcome biases and double counting, it will have to care equally for the satisfaction of every person's self-regarding preferences only: the filtering out of other- regarding preferences at both levels has nothing to do with the separation of the two levels. Moreover, the f~ct that people's self-regarding pref- erences, as aggregated by any unbiased utilitarian calculus, can be al- lowed to vary without limits shows that utilitarianism, at both the per- sonal and the social level, is in some sense "liberal" or "non-perfectionis- tic". It does not show that the ethical principle that defines appropriate personal conduct can consistently diverge from the one that defines appropriate institutional design, let alone that it must do so. Thus, despite some appearances, utilitarian distinctions have proved 78 PHILIPPE VAN PARUS no more able than our managerial dilemmas to support the strong claim that the principles of individual mora I behaviour cannot coincide with the principles of social justice. The dichotomic view, however, only makes the weaker claim that the former need not coincide with the latter. This view is forcefully expressed in John Rawls's recent writings. 2. Rawls's conception of a well-ordered society. According to Rawls's (1971, 453-4) original characterization, a well- ordered society is "a society in which everyone accepts and knows that the others accept the same principles of justice, and the basic institutions satisfy and are known to satisfy these principles". Hence, "its members have a strong and normally effective desire to act as the principles of justice require". In so far as the difference principle is concerned, the concrete meaning of this "normally effective desire" is vividly suggested in the connection Rawls (1971, 105) establishes earlier between this principle and "a natural meaning of fraternity": "Members of a family commonly do not wish to gain unless they can do so in ways that further the interests of the rest. Now wanting to act on the difference principle has precisely this consequence." Such formulations strongly support the view that in Rawls's ideal of a just society, maximin does not only shape the institutions, but also guides people's personal conduct. This is, however, the most fundamental point on which Rawls (1993a, xvi) has changed his position since the publication of his first book. In his more recent writings, he still defines a well-ordered society, the subject of "strict compliance theory", as a society in which "(nearly) everyone strictly complies with, and so abides by, the principles of justice" (Rawls 1990, §5.1). But he stresses that the account of the well- ordered society he offered in A Theory of Justice (TJ) was inconsistent. "The fact of a plurality of reasonable but incompatible comprehensive doctrines - the fact of reasonable pluralism - shows that, as used in TJ, the idea of a well-ordered society of justice as unfairness is unrealistic. This is because it is inconsistent with realizing its own principles under the best of foreseeable conditions." (Rawls 1993a, xvii). To understand this, one needs to see that, according. to TJ's account, "the members of any well-ordered society [ ... ] accept not only the same conception of justice but also the same comprehensive doctrine of which SOCIAL JUSTICE AND INDIVIDUAL ETHICS 79 that conception is a part, or from which it can be derived" (Rawls 1990, §55.4). But this "fails to take into account the condition of pluralism to which [Tf's] own principles lead" (ibid. §55.5). "Given the free institu- tions that conception itself enjoins, we can no longer assume that citizens generally, even if they accept justice as fairness [Le. Rawls's two prin- ciples of justice] as a political conception, also accept the particular comprehensive view to which it might seem in TJ to belong. We now assume citizens hold two distinct views; or perhaps better, their overall view has two parts: one part can be seen to be, or to coincide with, a political conception of justice; the other part is a (fully or partially) comprehensive doctrine to which the political conception is in some manner related." (ibid. §55.5) Whereas a comprehensive moral doctrine is "one that applies to all subjects and covers all values", a political conception "focuses on the political (in the form of the basic structure), -which is but a part of the domain of the moral" (ibid. §5.3). And it is precisely because commitment to the political doctrine does not entail commitment to the corresponding comprehensive doctrine that realizing the former can be "realistically utopian" (ibid. §5.1, my emphasis). "By contrast, a free democratic society well-ordered by any comprehensive doctrine, religious or secular, is surely utopian in the pejorative sense. Achieving it would in any case require the oppressive use of state power. This is as true of the liberalism of rightness as fairness [the comprehen- sive moral doctrine corresponding to justice as fairness], as it is of the Christianity of Aquinas and Luther." (ibid. §55.5) Does this new formulation of the ideal of a well-ordered society provide the dichotomists with the support they are looking for? Does it provide the resources required to resist the entailment from maximin justice to maximin conduct? Certainly not according to a lineage of critics who have accused Rawls of explicitly allowing a far wider range of inequalities than consistency with his own conception should permit. s For this criticism - which has been articulated most recently and systematic- ally by G.A. Cohen (1992a, 1992b) but goes back to Thomas Grey (1973, 316-25) in a leftish variant and to Jan Narveson (1976, 7-19) in a rightish variant - presupposes, as we shall see, that such a cut between the two parts of a citizens' overall morality cannot be made, and in particular that strict compliance with a maximin conception of justice must entail maximin conduct. Let us briefly examine the general structure of this line of criticism by focusing on the version offered by G.A. 80 PHILIPPE V AN PARIJS Cohen, before scrutinizing the threat it poses for the dichotomists' stance. 3. Cohen's egalitarian challenge Suppose that everyone is committed to a maximin conception of justice such as the one encapsulated in Rawls's (1971) difference principle. It is commonly believed and said, including by Rawls himself, that even in this sort of context inaximin will diverge from equality because the incentives created by income inequalities make it possible to give more to the worst off than the latter would get under strict equality. But why should that be the case ? If I am committed to maximin and could get more than others on the market because of the talents I possess, surely I shall not exploit this possibility and shall accept instead to do the same job for no more pay than the others, thus making it possible (say, through lower prices or higher transfers) to. maximize the real income of the worst off without any departure from equality. If everyone's behaviour con- forms to the difference principle, the latter will justify no such inequali- ties. Or, put differently, if you take seriously Rawls's idea that, in a just or well-ordered society, people are committed to the principles of justice that underlie the institutions, then maximin justice demands that incomes be equalized. This is the claim, in its simplest formulation. But there are two compelling reasons, both acknowledged by Cohen, why this proposition cannot possibly be sustained in this form. Firstly, income on its own does not provide an appropriate metric for a plausible interpretation of the difference principle. This is the case not only bec- ause restricting attention to income would lead one to neglect the other dimensions of socio-economic advantages explicitly mentioned in canon- ical formulations of the difference principle (wealth, powers and preroga- tives, the social bases of self-respect), but also, more relevantly, because it would lead one to neglect the unequal distribution of the length and irksomeness of labour. It is in no way inconsistent with a commitment to the difference principle, plausibly interpreted, to say : "I claim more income than others, but no more than what is required to match the burden of doing. more hours of work or a more strenuous job" or "I accept less income than others, but on condition that my work load is correspondingly decreased, using some meaningful metric for measuring burdens". Asking whether the difference principle justifies incentive- SOCIAL JUSTICE AND INDIVIDUAL ETHICS 81 providing inequalities amounts to asking whether it justifies rewards that go beyond the sheer compensation of arduous work, which can be con- strued as equalizing unequal situations. Cohen's (l992a, 296-7; 1992b, section 4) claim is that there is no justification for payments to talented people that go beyond this compensation and thereby constitute genuine inequalities. The many philosophers who have pondered at length about the fortunes of basketball player Wilt Chamberlain and his younger brother hockey player Wayne Gretsky will need little convincing to believe that such inequalities can still be very considerable. Secondly, some inequalities may be needed to make it possible (as opposed to attractive) for the talented to perform the job at which they would be socially most useful. I think I can remember, for example, that during the week preceding the Oxford-Cambridge rowing contest, the Oxford University rowing team was hosted by its captain's college and given lavish meals, in order to enable them (not motivate them) to win a victory that would bring great pride to all Oxonians. Similarly, a stressed manager's expensive holidays are arguably needed to enable her and her family to live the sort of life they have to live without going crazy. In such cases, genuine inequality (beyond sheer compensation for doing the job: both the rowers and the manager may actually enjoy it) may be justified, though not justified qua subjective incentives. To use Cohen's (l992a, 311; 1992b, section 8) formulations, such inequalities are "strictly necessary", "necessary apart from human choice", "neces- sary apart from people's chosen intentions", they reflect "purely objective feasibility sets". Their point is to enable, not to stimulate. Such genuine inequalities, Cohen (1992b, section 4) concedes, are consistent with everyone being committed to the difference principle, but he ascribes them to "special circumstances" and distinguishes them from the "normal case", in which inequalities work as incentives. 4. Subjective compensation,' or the convergence o/maximin, equal- ity and self-interest. What matters to us here, however, is not the empirical question of how much ineqUality would still find room in Rawls's well-ordered society in the event that Cohen's claim (appropriately qualified) proves valid, but whether the latter is indeed valid. In a society whose institutions are 82 PHILIPPE VAN PARIJS shaped by the difference principle and whose members are committed to it, are the only legitimate inequalities those that are required to compen- sate for special burdens or to generate worthwhile capacities? In other words, do incentive payments have no place in a just society? To get a better grip on this question, let us try to imagine the func- tioning of a society that is not only equipped with institutions governed by the difference principle, but also consists in people committed to the latter. Should one, for example, require these people to find out how hard they would work spontaneously in the absence of institutions designed to maximally favour the worst off and then to work just as hard despite the redistributive mechanisms (a rather problematic and underspecified coun- terfactl,lal exercise)? Or should one require them to be constantly on the look out for the worst off in order to display their generosity? There seems to be a far simpler approach which asks the members of such a well-ordered society no more than a willing and honest participation in the working of appropriately designed institutions. Leaving out, for the sake of simplicity, the possibility of enabling inequalities, one particularly convenient construal of these institutions goes like this. 6 First, select at random some no-work-some-income option common to all the members of the society concerned, and call it the zero option. Next, ask each person what her reservation wage would be for each occupation (defined by type and length of labour) she could do, and accordingly draw 'her fair compensation curves, which specify, for each type of labour, the (possibly negative) level of pay required to make that person indifferent between various lengths of labour time and the zero option. Next, determine each person's productivity for each such oc- cupation. Finally, require people to choose occupations in such a way that the social surplus is maximized. The social surplus is here understood as the difference between the aggregate social product (net of capital used up) and the aggregate compensation of those who have contributed to it, as determined by the reservation wages just mentioned. This social sur- plus is to be distributed equally to all members of the society concerned, thus providing the common zero option. There is of course no reason why the fair compensation curves associated to any particular zero option picked at random should lead to socially optimal assignments that will generate a social surplus per head that matches exactly ,.the chosen zero option. The associated social surplus may fall short of or exceed what is needed to fund this option. The level of income that defines the latter is SOCIAL JUSTICE AND INDIVIDUAL ETHICS 83 appropriately chosen when the funds required to finance it exactly match the social surplus generated as a result of people taking up their socially optimal assignment among those they regard as equivalent to the zero option. Within this institutional framework, people's commitment to the difference principle simply requires them (1) to reveal the true pattern of their reservation wages and productivity patterns, so that their fair com- pensation curves can be worked out and their socially optimal assignment determined; and (2) to willingly accept the latter, as characterized by a particular type and length of labour. Before turning to the problems the scheme poses, let us note that it painlessly combines maximin, equality and free choice of occupation within each person's legitimate choice set made up of all subjectively equivalent occupations (with appropriate compensatory payments). It even seems able to generate, with choice sets thus shaped, a smooth conver- gence between commitment to justice and self-interest, the latter nega- tively defined as whatever, among the things a person cares about, does not reduce to or derive from a commitment to justice. For it suffices to increase very slightly (say, by €) the payment associated with the socially optimal option, for each person to choose out of self-interest the occupa- tion which will most contribute to the situation of the worst off, i.e. of everyone, since everyone enjoys a situation equivalent (in her own eyes, and forgetting about the €'s) to the zero option. Consequently, this picture of the implied institutional framework seems to fully substantiate Cohen's defensive insistence that he "do[es] not aim to impugn the integrity of a conception of justice which allows the agent a certain self-regarding prerogative" (Cohen 1992a, 314), and that "it is not true that, in the society [he has] in mind, a person would have to worry about unfortunate people every time he made an economic decision" (ibid. 316). Moreover, the basic setup just sketched can easily be extended from the choice of occupation to the choice of levels of effort within an oc- cupation. Material incentives, and hence inequalities, are not only said to be required to induce the talented to choose occupations which put their talents to productive use. Under the standard version of the so-called efficiency-wage approach to unemployment, for example, the effort is assumed to be a positive function of the wage rate because the higher the latter, the greater the fear of being dismissed. If the employer gave the worker no more than the latter's reservation wage, the worker would be indifferent between working and being sacked, and hence would not put 84 PHILIPPE VAN PARIJS as mU'ch effort in her work. But here again, if workers are committed to the difference principle, they ~ould reveal truthfully what levels of pay would exactly compensate them for various levels of effort. They could then be told not only what job to do, but also what level of effort to muster (which would not be the maximum feasible one, given the need for compensation), and they would comply, without thereby sacrificing themselves, since they would not be worse off (and could even be made better off by E) than 0 at lower levels of effort. Furthermore, the same framework can conceivably be extended from working to saving, i.e. to an area which Cohen does not consider but which is no less concerned by claims about the need for incentives. Given some common no-work, no-saving, some-income option, we could then (1) construct for each person the set of combinations of (financially compensated) work and (financially compensated) saving that are equivalent, using her own preferences, to this option, and (2) ask each person (possibly with an E signal) to select from this legitimate choice set the combination of work and saving behaviour that maximizes the sus- tainable social surplus. Whether in its simpler or in its more complex variant, one striking feature of this egalitarian institutional framework is that it does not re- quire any sacrifice of people's self-interest in addition to the truthful provision of the information the working of the institutions requires. The situation of the worst off will be maximized without any incentive pay- ment (apart from the negligible E'S), just as a result of people pursuing their self-interest within the choice set designed for each of them by the institutional framework. The proposal, however, also raises a number of difficulties, at least one of which I believe to be decisive. One essential feature of the proposed institutional setup is that the same type and amount of work (or the same type and amount of saving) will have to be rewarded differently depending on who performs it: the more distaste a person has for contributing to social production in a certain way, the higher the rate at which she will have to be compensated, at least if her contribution is worth having at that rate. Clearly, this feature makes the institutional scheme practically un- workable: each worker or saver would need to face a personalized, preference-specific set of wage and interest rates. But at the level of abstraction the present exercise is being conducted, this can hardly count as a decisive defect. More seriously, in order to determine the appropri- SOCIAL JUSTICE AND INDIVIDUAL ETHICS 85 ate differentiation of payments, one needs information that is entirely private: since the self-interest reflected in the fair compensation curves is not definitionally equivalent to the preference schedule that guides a person's choices, there is no way of checking the truth of a person's statements about her reservation wage or interest payments. And this arguably violates the publicity requirement which Rawls and others want any just institutional setup to meet. But above all, the key feature singled out above makes the scheme most questionable as an adequate expression of the egalitarian ideal. For although every person's situation will be, in her own eyes, equivalent to (or, taking the €'S into account, no worse than) some common baseline situation (the zero option), some people may end up in an objective situation that is far worse, in everyone's eyes, than some others, simply owing to their having more accommodating preferen- ces. Suppose, for example, that you and I can do only the same one job and that, whatever the number of working hours, I resent doing the job more than you do. Consequently, for any given number of hours, the criterion of fair compensation will require paying me more than you. (Surplus maximization may, but need not, ask you to perform more hours than me.) And my assignment (with the associated compensation) is then most likely to be universally preferred to yours. A setup that ends up giving me a universally preferred job because of my being fussier than you - or, to put it differently, because of my having, relative to you, an expensive taste for leisure - is not very credible as an adequate expres- sion of the egalitarian ideal. 5. Objective compensation; or maximin, equality and self-interest at odds Cohen (1992a, 296; 1992b, section 4) is not very explicit about the notion of "special burden" which allows higher remuneration to work as a "counterbalancing equalizer" "where work is specially arduous, or stressful". But the most plausible ways of spelling out the institutional framework called forth by his egalitarian ideal do not rest - if the ar- guments just stated are cogent, fortunately so - on a subjective notion of fair compensation, as does the proposal examined above. Along with Baker (1992, 109-10), he might rather be taken to assume that some objective, individually undifferentiated notion of burden can be used to play the role ascribed above to the subjective, person-specific disutility 86 PHILIPPE VAN PARIJS of working or saving. The formal structure sketched above then remains relevant: (1) for each level of the zero option, each type of activity and each individual, one draws a fair compensation curve - a set of work-income combina- tions equivalent to the zero option - which indicates the remuneration needed to cover the ~pecial burden incorporated in a certain number of hours of that activity; (2) among these equivalent combinations, people are asked to select the one that maximizes the social surplus (to be dis- tributed equally to all and thereby provide the income entering the zero option); and (3) the zero option is pitched at the highest sustainable level consistent with this process. But b~cause of the objective interpretation of the notion of burden, the implementation of this framework no longer raises the same problems of untractability and lack of publicity - there are no longer different rates of pay depending on some features of a person which only that person can know -, nor the same objection of ~nfairness - the work-shy no longer get a premium. But while solving these difficulties, the shift to an objective notion of burden creates another problem, of central importance, as we shall see, for the question of the relationship between maximin justice and in- dividual ethics. For one can now no longer bank on a guaranteed har- mony between the maximal improvement of the situation of the worst off and self-interested choice within the choice sets shaped by egalitarian institutions. Obviously, the various occupations (cum compensation) deemed equivalent by virtue of the objective notion of burden are no longer automatically equivalent according to the agents' preferences. Consequently, it can no longer be taken for granted that picking the surplus-maximizing element in the choice set drawn by the egalitarian institutions will involve no substantial cost, relative to other options in that set, in terms of the person's self-interest. The level of fair compen- sation associated to various occupations by this objective assessment will in general exceed for some people what is needed to match the disutility incurred, while falling short of it for some other people. Given the choice, the latter's self-interest may therefore strongly favour the zero option over the zero-option-objectively-equivalent occupation (for short, ZOE) which surplus maximization would recommend, and this time, therefore, an insignificant e would be incapable of reconciling maximin and self-interest by steering people's self-interested choices in the socially optimal direction. Note, moreover, that this tradeoff would not only arise SOCIAL JUSTICE AND INDIVIDUAL ETHICS 87 for those who would be undercompensated, relative to the disutility incurred, if they were assigned to their surplus-maximizing ZOE, but also for those who would then get exactly the right compensation or be over- compensated, as overcompensation may be even greater for some other, non-surplus-maximizing ZOE. This may seem to point to an unbridgeable conflict between equality, maximin and free occupational choice. If you let people free to choose their occupation, there is no reason to expect that people's choices in their egalitarian choice sets will select the surplus-maximizing option, and maximin will therefore generally diverge from equality. For example, choice-respecting egalitarian institutions seem bound to make you lose the services of an exceptionally gifted manager whose tastes are such that she would be subjectively undercompensated at the rate of pay that matches the objectively assessed burden of a managerial job. Given the choice, she may choose to do no work at all or opt for another, more relaxed oc- cupation (say, being a sculptor) whose objective burden, and hence pay, have been assessed at a lower level but for which she has a far greater liking, so that the lower pay is more than offset by the reduced stress, or by the greater intrinsic pleasure she derives from the job, or by the importance she attaches to her children and spouse no longer having to suffer her being away at unsuitable times. As a result of occupational choice being guided by this preference, exceptional managerial skills are left unused, and both the social surplus and the situation of the worst off remain at a lower level than would have been the case if the absence of free occupational choice had made it possible to effectively assign the sculptor to the manager job instead. However, formulating the conflict as one between maximin equality and freedom of occupation begs the central question of this article. For if commitment to the difference principle (whether constrained by free- dom of choice or unconstrained) implies accepting the surplus-maximizing assignment, then there is no conflict, in a well-ordered society, between maximin equality and free occupational choice, nor any reason to expect freely choosing but appropriately committed individuals to prevent e- quality from achieving the maximin. What the example of our manager- ially gifted sculptor illustrates is rather the possibility of a sharp conflict between maximin equality and self-interest, even when the choice is restricted to objectively equivalent options. Realizing this possibility forces us to ask the following question: 88 PHILIPPE V AN P ARIJS Does the ideal of a just society involve that people should always sacri- fice their self-interest to their commitment to the difference principle, by accepting the surplus-maximizIng assignment, however much they would (self-interestedly) prefer another, objectively equivalent occupation? Under the subjective compensation interpretation of equality, the question did not arise. But under the objective compensation interpretation, unless there is a close fit, not just an (uncontroversial) positive correlation, between what people like and what they are good at, it can take a very acute and worrying form. For what people need, if they are to sacrifice their self-interested .preferences, is not just a strong commitment to the difference principle, but also a full trust in the way in which the objective burden of the various occupations is being assessed. This puts a lot. of weight on the possibility of working out a meaning- ful objective notion of burden. While it is clear that the latter should not be person-specific, it is also clear that it cannot be completely discon- nected from the disutility incurred by the people performing the activity concerned. If everyone prefers doing' A to doing B, one cannot sensibly associate a heavier objective burden, and hence a higher level of fair compensation, to the doing of A. But how is this burden to be defined? Perhaps as average disutility, the latter being measured by the reservation wage with the zero option as the only alternative option? But what is the relevant sample? The whole of the active population of the society con- cerned? Only those among them who have the skills required to do the job? Only those among them who know what they are talking about, because they have had an opportunity to try the job? And what if some would not do the job whatever the wage, thus making the job's average disutility infinite? If simple (or more sophisticated) averaging is no good, perhaps we could appeal to some democratic procedure. But even h~aving aside the fact that any workable democratic procedure would involve delegating the assessment to an appropriate group of experts, which would take us back to square one, what would be the credentials of majority rule on the presumably factual issue of how burdensome a particular activity is? I am not claiming that these few remarks make total nonsense of the notion of objective burden. But they suffice to show, I believe, that any such notion is bound to remain conceptually problematic. Consequently, one could never feel on firm ground when turning down the complaint of someone who believes to be unfairly treated, i.e. considers herself unjus- SOCIAL JUSTICE AND INDIVIDUAL ETHICS 89 tifiably made worse off than others in terms of income-burden bundles, as a result of being asked to accept, out of commitment to the difference principle, her surplus-maximizing ZOE. This does not force us to aban- don the whole approach. But it seems hard to escape the need to protect oneself against serious injustices by providing every worker with the fol- lowing sort of safeguard: apart from her surplus-maximizing option, she can also choose, if she prefers, the common zero option to which the latter is supposed to be objectively equivalent. This seems to be, given the specific interpretation of the egalitarian institutional framework adopted here, a natural way of interpreting Cohen's concession to Scheffler that "every person has a right to pursue self-interest to some reasonable extent" (1992a, 302) or his emphatic refusal "to impugn the integrity of a conception of justice which allows an agent a certain self-regarding prerogative" (1992a, 314). One could of course think of more restrictive or complicated ways of making some room for the pursuit of self-interest. For example, one could exempt a worker from her socially optimal assignment only if the cost to her of accepting it would be great, and the benefit to society rather small. Or one could imagine that each person would be allowed to pick from a subset of ZOE's involving some contribution on her part rather than to go for the zero option. But apart from its simplicity, the safeguard has the great advantage of meeting what would seem to be a minimum con- dition of any fair scheme of work compensation, namely that it should make sure that no worker ends up worse off than if she had been left to do nothing. Even those who feel inclined towards more subtle or guarded ways of making some .room for self-interest should therefore find it worthwhile exploring what follows from introducing the safeguard. 6. Why incentive payments can be just after all But here comes the crux. For once such a safeguard is introduced (ar- guably as a minimalist way of spelling out Cohen's concession), there is no longer any reason to believe that, in a well-ordered society of suitably committed people (and abstracting, as usual, from enabling inequalities), maximin will necessarily coincide with equality, nor therefore that incen- tive payments should be ruled out. Once people are left the choice bet- ween their socially optimal occupation and the zero option, the (largest 90 PHILIPPE V AN P ARIJS sustainable) social surplus and hence the zero option will obviously be smaller than if their choice had been restricted to the former. One way of weakening this negative effect consists in assigning to each worker who would otherwise choose the zero option the socially most beneficial among the ZOE's not blocked by the safeguard. This is no doubt better as far as maximin is concerned, while still being perfectly egalitarian according to the objective metric. But there is better still. 'It may be possible, consistently with the safeguard, to generate a higher social surplus if people are not only given access to some suboptimal ZOE's, but also to some supra-ZOE's, to some options that are superior to the zero option according to the objective metric. Paying more than the objectively fair compensation may make a productive worker relinquish the zero option in favour of an occupation that will contribute more to the surplus than any of her safeguard-proof ZOE's, despite the additional compensation required. In the case of the exceptionally gifted but not very keen manager referred to above, for example, it may be better, as far as maximin is concerned, to ask her to be a sculptor rather than remain idle. But it may be even better to provide her with a wage sufficiently high to make her prefer being a manager to doing nothing. For if this higher wage still allows the manager's net contribution to the social surplus to be greater than it would have been with the best ZOE occupation she would have accepted, then, assuming the other workers' compensation is unaffected, social surplus maximization, and hence maximin, will deviate from (bu- rden-sensitive) equality. Ignoring this potential by sticking to payments that do not exceed the assessed objective burden, in other words, amounts to keeping the social surplus, and hence the situation of the worst off, lower than it could be. Maximin no longer necessarily coincides with equality once a person's commitment to the difference principle is no longer interpreted as entailing the lexical priority of accepting her sur- plus-maximizing ZOE over all the other moral and non-moral considera- tions that make up her self-interest. Once this is admitted, incentives of the standard type are not much further down the road. For what has been said so far supposes that one can identify the gifted but reluctant workers and award them the premium required to make them self-interestedly prefer their optimal assignment to the zero option. This supposes in turn that different people may receive different incomes for the same job, depending on the nature of their SOCIAL JUSTICE AND INDIVIDUAL ETHICS 91 preferences. This does not take us completely back to the subjective compensation scheme and to the expensive-taste difficulty which proved fatal to it. For paying the fussy more than the keen is now no longer an embarrassing component of the egalitarian ideal, but a by-product of the pursuit of maximin in a context in which self-regarding considerations are allowed to play some role. Nonetheless, this person-specific compensation scheme raises the other difficulties mentioned in connection with the subjective compensation scheme, notably those grounded in its reliance on essentially private information, and this can reasonably be deemed sufficient to discard it. The alternative consists in conceding the supra-ZOE pay, not only to the reluctant managers, but to anyone else doing the same job. While increasing the net contribution of the reluctant manager, the introduction of the premium now also reduces the net contribution of her no less productive but keener fellow managers. This will no doubt make the labour allocator very cautious about awarding any significant premium. It will also further complicate her job, for what was socially optimal for a person to do if she were paid no more than the objectively fair compen- sation may no longer be socially optimal once she is paid an extra pre- mium. So, instead of adding this further headache to a job that was already unmanageable anyway, the labour allocator may wisely decide to give over to a sufficiently competitive and self-interest-guided labour market the task of allocating people to jobs and determining their gross incomes, while converting herself into a tax collector. The social surplus is then being maximized, not through the filling of jobs and the fixing of wages, but through the sustainable-yield-maximizing taxation of every type of job, taking both supply and demand reactions into account, and the equal distribution of this yield. The two approaches are not quite equivalent. For example, whereas the central allocation method described allows only upward deviations from the ZOE baseline, nothing prevents in principle taxation from turning some jobs which a sufficient number of appropriately skilled workers are keen to do into infra-ZOE's, i.e. occupations paid less than is justified by the objective assessment of the associated burden. Indeed, in the taxation approach, the very notion of objective burden has become superfluous. But I very much doubt this makes any significant difference. Let us bear in mind, in particular, that the equal and unconditional distri- bution of the surplus guarantees that no worker will be worse off while 92 PHILIPPE VAN PARIJS working than under the zero option. Let us also bear in mind that scarce talents may command large gross incomes as potential employers compete to hire them, but that yield-maximizing taxation should manage to extract the bulk of this factor rent. How much the resulting income distribution would diverge from objective-burden-sensitive equality is of course a question that can only be settled on an empirical basis. But on the plau- sible assumption that there cannot be that many people who particularly hate doing what they are particularly good at, one can safely conjecture that the income inequalities that would survive yield-maximizing taxation will not be far greater nor far different from those implied by any sen- sible notion of fair compensation. In this light, it remains quite possible - indeed, if the facts are not wildly different from what I think they are, extremely plausible - that "a modest right of self-interest [of the sort acknowledged above] seems insufficient to justify the range of inequality, the extremes of wealth and poverty, that actuall y obtain in [contemporary Britain]" (Cohen 1992a, 302-3). But is the range of inequality thus justified any narrower than the range of inequality allowed by the conventional interpretation of the difference principle? Cohen's concession, as elaborated above step by step, seems to lead to legitimizing all incentive payments that boost the social surplus, and hence the situation of the worst off. Does this mean that people's commitment to the difference principle, once softened by the safeguard, has no impact whatever on legitimate inequalities? Not quite. To start with, in the institutional context sketched above, each person committed to the difference principle can be expected to report truthfully her gainful activities and pay honestly whatever tax rates the surplus- maximizing institutions attach to the pay and perks these activities give access to. Being able to bank on this sort of behaviour will enable a well- ordered society to collect and distribute a higher social surplus than would be the case in a society whose members are not so committed. Even in such a society, higher tax rates will induce, owing to the safe- guard, lower levels of performance. But they will not widen the gap between actual and reported activities. Thus, safeguard-checked commit- ment demands that people should not cheat. It also demands that they should not use their bargaining power, especially their collective bar- gaining power as exercised in strikes and similar actions, in order to resist tax pressure more than they would do by adjusting parametrically to the tax structure, i.e. by simply reducing individually their supply of SOCIAL JUSTICE AND INDIVIDUAL ETHICS 93 labour or capital as the tax rate increases. In a well-ordered society, the availability of the highest zero option that can be made available to all provides the legitimate safeguard. Free collective bargaining, or an unrestricted right to strike, cannot be part of the picture. In other words, it is not enough not to cheat the institutions, it is equally important not to bend them.s These are two important features of economic behaviour, whether individual or collective, that follow from a commitment to maximin justice, understood as willing compliance with institutions that aim to maximize the situation of the worst off. But among the choices left open by such institutions and the two constraints on individual behaviour just mentioned, people can and should be left free to pursue their self-interest - broadly understood, remember, as anything that does not reduce to or derive from a concern with achieving justice as characterized, including for example visiting an old aunt or supporting Greenpeace's action in the Antarctic. And if this is conceded, it follows, along the path followed above, that incentive payments - the rewarding of talents over and above what is needed to compensate the objective burden associated to their productive use (and to make the latter possible) - are legitimate in some quite plausible circumstances, namely in those circumstances in which the sustainable social surplus would be smaller without them, owing to the room granted to self-interest-guided choice. There will of course be people who will book a substantial "produ- cer's surplus", i.e. enjoy the benefit of a large difference between their actual pay and their reservation pay, as a result of such incentive pay- ments being allowed. But this also happens if the pay matches exactly the assessed burden, as soon as the latter is not defined in terms of person- specific disutility. More seriously, even with perfectly enforced maximin institutions, skills inequalities and/or various obstacles to the clearing of the labour market may well generate situations of dominance, i.e. of unanimous strict preference for one job situation over another or over the zero option. There is no question that these would be genuine inequali- ties. But once the concern to maximize the objectively worst income- burden bundle is constrained, as a way of making room for legitimate self-regarding considerations, by the possibility of choosing the zero option (or other, socially superior alternatives), then such inequalities are justified. Under perfectly operating maximin institutions, some job situa- tions may be superior to others in everyone's eyes. But any attempt to tax 94 PHILIPPE VAN PARIJS away such universally recognized advantages necessarily leads to a smaller redistributable surplus, as a result of some of the people taxed more heavily legitimately shifting to occupations that yield smaller net contributions to this surplus. 7. Why most incentive payments are nonetheless unjust, or the unexpected alliance of justice and patriotism Even on Cohen's premises, it thus turns out, some genuine incentive payments are justified. But my guess is that the inequalities so justified are of such a modest scope that not only Rawls but also Cohen would feel quite comfortable about condoning them. If this is the case, the apparent clash between left liberalism and radical egalitarianism has melted away. And since there is no point in insisting stubbornly on differences that vanish under scrutiny, radical egalitarians would simply have to shelve their interesting but misguided challenge and rally behind the left liberal flag. Or at least so they would have to do if one could reason, as we have done so far, within the boundaries of a closed economy. But once this assumption is lifted, the picture becomes very different indeed. We are then led to considerations that rescue the importance of Cohen's chal- lenge, but also have some other, rather puzzling implications. Let me briefly sketch these considerations and return, by the same token, to our initial question about the implications. of a maximin theory of justice for individual ethics. Suppose first that people can legitimately leave the country with their skills and other assets, if this is what their self-interest tells them to do. The agents' legitimate choice sets are then no longer basically shaped by the fact that the zero option should be available to all and that institutions should maximin people's situations, bearing this safeguard in mind. If agents have the option of supplying their labour and capital abroad and if the country concerned can attract precious factors from the outside world, then, whether or not the other countries each have their own maximin institutions, the situation is deeply altered. For the condition that needs to be met if a person is to choose her socially preferred occupation is no longer that she should regard it as preferable to the zero option (and other ZOE's), but that she should regard it as preferable to the most attractive option abroad. How attractive this possibilityis to the person SOCIAL JUSTICE AND INDIVIDUAL ETHICS 95 concerned obviously depends on the subjective cost of supplying abroad the factors one owns and on the prices these factors command in other countries, which will in turn depend both on the overall level of develop- ment of these countries and on their distributive institutions. Clearly, under such circumstances, just as in the actual world, the owners of potentially mobile and widely valued factors of production will be able to earn, even without any cheating or bending, far higher returns than in the world assumed so far. For the tax elasticity of the supply of these factors (essentially capital and highly skilled labour) tends to be very high, i.e. the amounts of these factors which a country can hope to retain or attract tends to be highly responsive to increases or decreases in their post-tax returns, and the maximin criterion will therefore lead to selecting very low, though yield-maximizing, tax rates. But is this picture consistent with the assumption that all members of the society concerned are committed to the difference principle? In other words, must disloyalty to one's country be assimilated to cheating or bending, and hence ruled out, or rather to choosing the zero option, and hence. legitimized by some variant of our safeguard? There is a strong prima facie case in favour of the first answer. If commitment to the difference principle implies that people will not want to cheat by con- cealing some of their gains in their home country, while still conceivably making a very sizeable contribution to the situation of the worst off in their country through the taxes they payor the employment they create, then surely commitment to the difference principle must also rule out that people may care so little about their countrymen that they may want to send their capital abroad or to move out altogether with their productive talents in a way that avoids maximin taxation in their home country. In other words, if one is committed to contributing as much as possible to improving the situation of the worst off in one's society, one must a fortiori be committed to sticking with this society - not whatever hap- pens perhaps, but as long as the soc.iety's institutions remain just. This argument, however, cannot be right. For if it were, then it would be even less legitimate to opt for the zero option. At least those who choose to leave the country altogether are not sucking the social surplus. So, if commitment to the difference principle makes it bad to quit, it must make it even worse to get a free ride or, more gener all y, to get a share in the surplus that exceeds the productive contribution one chooses to make. Or conversel y, if a safeguard I egitimatel y protects the 96 PHILIPPE VAN PARIJS desire I may have to surf rather than work, should it not also allow me to move abroad, at a lesser cost to my society, because I fell in love with a foreign culture, a foreign landscape or a foreign woman? The argument, however, can be rephrased in a way that is not vul- nerable to this objection. Let us look at the issue from the standpoint of the original position: we do not know what conception of the good life we shall have nor what talents we shall be endowed with, but we do know which society we belong to. In order to keep our life options open both at home and abroad, we shall certainly not commit ourselves to contributing to the surplus as much as we can. But in order to give ourselves the firmest possible real basis for making any choice we may want to make in case we turn out to have the poorest endowment, we shall not only choose to introduce maximin institutions but also commit ourselves to not cheating nor bending them. These institutions will have to involve the yield-maximizing taxation of incomes earned abroad as well as at home, and the matching individual duties will have to require the truthful reporting of foreign no less than of domes tic earnings. Nothing said so far requires that the members of a well-ordered society be subjected to a special duty of patriotism. For the duty not to cheat, and in particular to honestly report any foreign income, seems sufficient to check the downward pressure on the social surplus that would otherwise result from actual or potential international factor mobil- ity. This ignores, however, the crucial question of what defines, for redistribution purposes, membership in the society concerned. Whether it is permanent residence or formal citizenship, it is clear that the duty not to cheat offers only very poor protection against the pressure of international mobility if membership can easily be changed. If the institu- tions were to prohibit emigration (whether interpreted as a change of permanent residence or of citizenship status), the duty not to cheat would encompass the duty not to emigrate and the problem would disappear. But such an institutional prohibition would clearly violate what Rawls and many others would count among people's fundamental liberties. And so would, presumably, the imposition of prohibitive costs on prospective emigrants, such as the reimbursement of educational expenses, or of the present value of their skills, to the society they are leaving. This is why a special duty of patriotism needs to enter the picture. Such a duty does not need to require that one should never use the insti- tutionally guaranteed right to emigrate. What it must require is rather that SOCIAL JUSTICE AND INDIVIDUAL ETHICS 97 one should not emigrate for the wrong reason, i.e. modify one's resi- dence or citizenship status in order to enjoy a more favourable tax treat- ment. What generates strong constraints on the effective operation of an open economy's maximin institutions in a large world is not that its members may want to relinquish their membership because they fell in love with foreign people or foreign landscapes, but only that they may want to do so because of their interest in maximizing their post-tax in- comes. If they endorse maximin institutions, it would be inconsistent for the best endowed members of a society not only to consider cheating but also to consider escaping in response to high taxation. For the conse- quence would be that the objective of the maximin institutions would be defeated: precious little could be collected for redistribution to the worst off, both because of actual cheating or escaping and even more because of credible threats to cheat or escape. Knowing which society they belong to, people in the original position will protect themselves against this risk by committing themselves to behaving not only honestly but also patriot- ically, in the restricted sense of refusing to consider relinquishing mem- bership in their society for the wrong sort of reason. If the society's members can be relied on not only to refrain from cheating (and bending), but also to refrain from moving out in search of higher returns, then the constraints on the society's attempt to make its worst off members as well off as possible are greatly loosened, and the size of the incentive payments that will sustainably maximize the situation of the worst off will be far smaller than if tax rates had to keep subjecting themselves to the ruthless discipline of a highly responsive world finan- cial market or of an ipcreasingly integrated international market for skilled labour. Of course, how great a loss can be avoided in this way will greatly vary as a function of the size of the territory controlled by the relevant tax authority, of the society's relative prosperity, of the distinctness of its language and culture, of the charm of its climate and countryside, and of many other factors. But the very modest extent to which people actually alter their place of residence or their citizenship in order to avoid taxes· should not make us underestimate the impact of potential emigration on the current and, even more, the future shape and size of redistributive policies. The growing asymmetry between the taxation of capital and labour income and the erosion of the progres- siveness of income taxation in several countries can plausibly be inter- preted as two clear signs of growing pressures in an ever more open - 98 PHILIPPE V AN P ARIJS and unpatriotic - world. One implication of this argument, if it is correct, is that - after all - Cohen is right and Rawls is wrong on the issue of whether (the bulk of) surplus-enhancing incentive payments are justified, or at least that Rawls would be wrong if what he had in mind was an open economy in a large world of the sort we live in. In a hypothetical closed economy, whatever incentive payments would be paid to self-interest-guided econo- mic agents under maximin institutions can be justified, because maximin requires them, despite"a universal commitment to the difference principle, as soon as self-regarding considerations are allowed to guide people's choice with the zero option as a common baseline. In an open economy, this would not be the case. Some part, and probably by far the greatest part, of the incentive payments paid to self-interest-guided economic agents under maximin institutions would then remain unjustified, because they would only be needed as a consequence of the widespread adoption of an attitude that is inconsistent with a commitment to the difference principle. 8. Rawlsians: not Christians but patriots? What constraints, if any, does a commitment to maximin justice impose on one's individual ethics? The (very partial) answer we are ending up with can be summed up as follows. Once maximin institutions are in plage, commitment to maximin does entail a duty not to cheat or bend these institutions, and strict compliance with this duty will enable the maximin to be far more egalitarian than it would otherwise be. But it does not entail a moral duty to help those poorer than oneself. It "is not inconsistent with such a duty, but performance of the latter would be a expression of love, charity or caring, not an implication of a commitment to maximin justice, as we have come to interpret it. In a well-ordered society, being committed to the difference principle does not force us to find it despicable or objectionable to spend much of one's time and money collecting Indian totems or supporting the local soccer team, at the expense of doing everything within one's power to improve the situation of the worst off, providing of course the time and money thus used do not exceed what we get allotted by maximin institutions. To be honest, this negative conclusion is not particularly relevant to SOCIAL JUSTICE AND INDIVIDUAL ETHICS 99 the moral choices we face in our daily lives, such as, those mentioned in the first few sentences of this article. For we undoubtedly live in a badly ill-ordered society, and this leads to a different set of questions. In such circumstances, could we, for example, allow ourselves to be less honest, less cooperative, less patriotic than we would need to be in a well-ordered society, whether because the institutions are not to be trusted to generate, collect and distribute the social surplus in an efficient way, or because others do not do what the institutions expect them to do? Or should we rather be more demanding on ourselves, for example because it is up to us, in our private conduct, to do part of what the institutions of a well- ordered society would do, and because it is also up to us, in our political conduct, to fight e~ergeticall y for a juster institutional setup? I am not sure what overarching criterion could be applied in this balancing exer- cise, and there is little in the arguments of this article that may be helpful on this issue. My hunch, however, is that the second set of considerations is bound to weigh far more heavily, at any rate for all those (probably you and certainly me among them) who are better off than they would be in a just society. One cannot consistently claim to be committed to a maximin conception of justice and complacently enjoy privileges one can only be granted because the institutional setup violates this conception. Even if Rawlsians need not be Christians in a well-ordered society, they may well, after all, have to be (something like) Christians in the real world. Even in a hypothetical well-ordered society, however, it is not enough for Rawlsians to refrain from cheating their maximin institutions and from using their bargaining power in order to force redistribution down. They may not have to be Christians, but they will have to be patriots, in the limited sense of refusing to pull out of their society for the sake of collecting higher post-tax incomes elsewhere. Unless the members of our society - and also those of other societies - are patriotic in this sense, concern with maximin will force our institutions to pay large unjustified incentive payments to th'e holders of precious factors. There is, it must be conceded, one alternative to such a patriotic commitment. It consists in hoisting the maximin institutions from the local to the global level, from the-nation state to the world community. This is not, how- ever, the way Rawls (1993b) himself conceives of global justice. The just law of peoples, in his view, is not the one on which the representatives of individuals would settle in a global original position in which they 100 PHILIPPE V AN PARIJS ignore which society they belong to. It is one on which the represen- tatives of well-ordered societies would settle behind a suitably redesigned veil of ignorance, and it will include no stronger redistributive institution than mutual aid in the event of famines and other disasters. But if this is the way Rawlsians need to conceive of global justice, then, as the world market strengthens its grip on a growing number of countries, it becomes every day more crucial that Rawlsians should also be patriots. In so far as Rawlsianism rejects the global maximin of a world society while at the same time shying away from patriotism, it can only turn into the ideolo- gical justification of a world-wide breakdown of redistributive institutions in the name of maximin constrained by free exit. 9 And even if the global maximin is recognized, as I believe it should, as the only coherent long- term ideal, patriotic commitments would provide a welcome help to relieve pressure on each country's (or each region's or each confedera- tion' s) redistributive setup in the long interim period that is bound to elapse before sufficiently powerful interpersonal transfer systems can be introduced at the global level. Hence, whether or not consistent Rawlsians can stop short of ad- vocating a global maximin, patriotism is a central ingredient in the in- dividual ethics called forth by the conception of justice they assert. Universite catholique de Louvain Chaire Hoover d'ethique economique et sociale 3 Place Montesquieu, B-1348 Louvain-Ia-Neuve, Belgium NOTES * This article is a significantly abridged version of a paper that grew, in directions I did not anticipate, out of a sequence of talks given in various places in the course of the academic year 1993-1994: at a meeting of the Institut International de Philosophie on "Public and private morality" (Liege, 2 September 1992), at the Philosophy Department of Bristol University (Bristol, 12 February 1993), at the conference on "Democracy and consensus. A debate around John Rawls" (Oxford, 13 February 1993, at the Philosophy Department of the Universite du Quebec (Montreal, 7 April 1993), at the Legal Theory Workshop of Yale Law School (New Haven, 8 Apri11993), SOCIAL JUSTICE AND INDIVIDUAL ETHICS 101 at the Seminaire de philosophie contemporaine of the U niversite catholique de Louvain (Louvain-Ia-Neuve, 22 April 1993), at the Faculty of economic and social sciences of the Universite catholique de Fribourg (Fribourg, 11 May 1993), at the Theology Faculty of the Universite de Geneve (Geneva, 12 May 1993), at the Philosophy Department of Fu Jen University (Taipei, 29 May 1993), at the Faculty of Sociology and Politics of the Universitat Autonoma de Barcelona (Barcelona, 19 June 1993) and at the 1993 meeting of the September Group (London, 3 September 1993), I am particularly grateful to Bruce Ackerman, Karl-Otto-Apel, Christian Amsperger, Ruth Barcan-Marcus, Brian Barry, Sam Bowles, Chris Bertram, John Broome, Jerry Cohen, Jocelyne Couture, Genevieve de Pesloiian, Toni Domenech, Paul Dumouchel, Ronald Dworkin, Owen Fiss, Marc Fleurbaey, Andreas Follesdal, Keith Graham, Steven Lukes, Adam Morton, Robert Nadeau, Kai Nielsen, Onora O'Neill, John Passmore, Michael Rosen, Dan Weinstock, Erik Wright and' above all John Baker and Joe Carens, for stimulating oral and/or written comments. All of them forced me and helped me to think harder about the issues touched upon in the article, but only some of this further thinking found its way into this abridged version. The com- plete version will appear in the newly founded European Journal of Philosophy. 1. Here, and throughout the remainder of this paper, "her" stands for "his or her" or "him or her", and "she" for "he or she" . 2. As a professor in a catholic University, I may perhaps be forgiven for using this convenient but admittedly parochial formulation. 3. See James Meade's (1973,52) statement that "ideal society would be one in which each citizen developed a real split personality, acting selfishly in the market place and altruistically at the ballot box" (quoted by Barry 1989, 394-5). Split personalities are not the out- come of a conflict beteen two moralities, but the instrument of a single one. . 4. On the former, see the discussion between Scanlon (1991) and Rawls (1993a, 179-80) on whether utilitarianism is a form of liberalism. On the latter, see the discussion between Dworkin (1977, 234-8), and, for example, Ten (1980, 30-3) and Ezorsky (1981) on the notion of "personal" preferences. 5. I shall return below (section 6) to the question of what does follow 102 PHILIPPE VAN P ARIJS for individual conduct, according to Rawls himself, from a commit- ment to justice as fairness as a purely political conception. 6. The present section and the following two are heavily indebted, more than is acknowledged in the footnotes of this abridged version, to discussions of equality and compensation by Joseph Carens (1981, 1985, 1986) John Baker (1987, 1992) and Brian Barry (1992). 7. I should say that I am exploring this interpretation of the egalitarian ideal because it is present in Cohen's critique of Rawls, not because I bel ieve it provides the most appealing approach. Some metric of opportunities (rather than of income-burden bundles) makes for a better fit with (at least) my moral intuitions, generalizes easily be- yond the sphere of production and dispenses with the problematic notion of objective burden (see Van Parijs 1990, 1991). However, some version of the central issues raised in this article arises also under the opportunity-egalitarian interpretation. 8. This twofold restriction on individual behaviour bears at least some resemblance with Rawls's (1990, §37.1) stipulation that, in a well- ordered society, "citizens accept existing institutions as just and usually have no desire to violate, or to renegociate, the terms of social cooperation, given their present and prospective social posi- tion. Here we suppose that political and social cooperation would quickly break down if everyone, or even many people, always acted self- or group- interestedly in a purely strategic, or game-theoretic fashion" (my emphasis). 9. Rawls (1990, §26.5; 1993b) speaks of a "suitably qualified right of emigration". But the qualifications he has in mind have nothing to do with the patriotic duty advocated here: "I shan't discuss these qualifi- cations. I have in mind, for example, that those properly convicted of certain sufficiently serious crimes may not be allowed to emigrate, pending serving their sentence" (Rawls 1990, §26.5, n 15). REFERENCES Baker, John. 1988. Arguing for Equality. London: Verso. Baker, John. 1992. An egalitarian case for basic income .. In Arguing for Basic Income. Ethical Foundations for a Radical Reform Ed. P. Van Parijs.London: Verso, 101-27. SOCIAL JUSTICE AND INDIVIDUAL ETHICS 103 Barry, Brian. 1989. Theories of Justice. London: Harvester-Wheatsheaf. Barry, Brian. 1992. Equality Yes, Basic Income No. In Ed. P. Van Parijs. Arguingfor Basic Income. Ethical Foundationsfor a Radical Reform. London: Verso, 128-40. Carens, Joseph H. 1981. Equality, Moral Incentives and the Market. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Carens, Joseph H. 1985. Compensatory justice and social institutions. Economics and Philosophy 1: 39-67. Carens, Joseph H. 1986. Rights and duties in an egalitarian society. Political Theory 14 (1): 31-49. Cohen, G.A. 1992a. Incentives, Inequality and Community. In The Tanner Lectures on Human Values Vol. XIII: Salt Lake City: Uni- versity of Utah Press, 261-329. Cohen, G.A. 1992b. The Pareto Argument for Inequality. Oxford: All Souls College, June 1992, 56 p. Ezorsky, Gertrud. 1981. On Refined U til itarianism . Journal of Philoso- phy 78: 156-9. Grey, Thomas C. 1973. The First Virtue. Stanford Law Review 25: 286- 327. Meade, James E. 1973. Theory of Economic Externalities. Leiden: Sij- thoff. Narveson, Jan F. 1976. A Puzzle about Economic Justice in Rawls's Theory. Social Theory and Practice 4: 1-27. Rawls, John. 1990. Justice as Fairness. A Restatement. Harvard Univer- sity, unpublished lecture notes. Rawls, John. 1993a. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia Univer- sity Press. Rawls, John. 1993b. The Law of Peoples. Amnesty International Lecture, Oxford University, 12 February 1993. Scanlon, Tim M. 1991. The Moral Basis of Interpersonal Comparisons. In Eds. J. Elster & J .E. Roemer. Interpersonal Comparisons afWell- being. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 17-44. Ten, C.L. 1980. Mill on Liberty. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Van Parijs, Philippe. 1990. Equal Endowments as Undominated Diver- sity. Recherches Economiques de Louvain 56: 327-356. Van Parijs, Philippe. 1991. Why Surfers Should be Fed. The liberal case for an unconditional basic income. Philosophy and Public Affairs 20: 101-31. work_ejx6zzsrnjdclicvwtvms43asm ---- The British Crime Survey (BCS) showed that there were 10.7 millions crimes committed against adults living in private households in England and Waes in 2008/09, 8.7 million fewer crimes than in 1995. (Table 9.2) According to the BCS in England and Wales in 2008/09, victims of domestic violence were most likely to report being a repeat victim, with 38 per cent of domestic violence victims experiencing this crime more than once in the 12 months prior to interview. (Figure 9.4) The number of crimes reported to the police in England and Wales in which a firearm excluding air weapons had been used was 8,208 in 2008/09, a fall of 17 per cent compared with the previous year. (Figure 9.6) In 2008, there was a total of £609.9 million worth of plastic card fraud losses on UK issued cards, the highest recorded since 1998, when £135.0 million worth of fraud losses occurred. Losses of £379.7 million (62 per cent) occurred in the UK, compared with £230.1 million (38 per cent) of fraud which occurred abroad. (Figure 9.8) Police officers from ethnic minority groups accounted for 4.4 per cent of total police officer strength in England and Wales at 31 March 2009. (Table 9.19) In 2008/09, a total of 31,259 complaint cases were made by members of the public against those serving with the police in England and Wales, an increase of 8 per cent on the previous year and the most complaints recorded in a single year since 1990. (Figure 9.21) C h ap ter 9 Download data by clicking the online pdf www.statistics.gov.uk/ socialtrends Crime and justice 126 Chapter 9: Crime and justice Social Trends 40: 2010 edition 9 Many people will be affected by crime during the course of their lives, either directly through loss or suffering, or indirectly through, for example, experiencing heightened levels of fear. This can restrict people’s behaviour, or mean that they feel they have to take additional security measures in the course of their daily life. Crime and its associated problems are a continuing concern for society and the Government. There are two main sources of statistics on crime levels: household population surveys of people’s experiences of crime, and police records of crime (see Measures of crime text box). Crime levels This chapter discusses the incidence and the prevalence of crime (see also Appendix, Part 9: Prevalence rates and incidence rates). The prevalence of crime, or the percentage of people who were victims, is covered in the Offences and victims section later in the chapter. The incidence of crime, or the number of crimes experienced, is analysed in this section. In 2008/09, there were 5.2 million crimes recorded by the police across the UK (Table 9.1), this was a fall of 5 per cent from 5.4 million offences in 2007/08. In England and Wales, recorded crime also fell by 5 per cent between 2007/08 and 2008/09, to reach 4.7 million notifiable offences. Nearly three-quarters (71 per cent) of recorded crimes in England and Wales were property crimes; these include theft and handling stolen goods, burglary, offences involving a vehicle, criminal damage and fraud and forgery. Almost a fifth (19 per cent) of all recorded crime involved violence against the person. The definition of crime in Northern Ireland is broadly comparable with that in England and Wales. The police in Northern Ireland recorded 110,000 crimes in 2008/09. Theft and handling stolen goods accounted for 24 per cent of all recorded crimes, a lower proportion than in England and Wales or Scotland. In Northern Ireland criminal damage and violence against the person formed higher proportions of recorded crime, at 26 per cent and 27 per cent respectively. Measures of crime There are two main measures of the extent of crime in the UK: surveys of the public, and crime recorded by the police. The British Crime Survey (BCS) interviews adults aged 16 and over who are living in private households in England and Wales. The Scottish Crime and Justice Survey (SCJS) and the Northern Ireland Crime Survey (NICS) interview adults aged 16 and over in Scotland and Northern Ireland respectively. In some ways the BCS, the SCJS and the NICS give a better measure of many types of crime than police-recorded crime statistics. These surveys show the large number of offences that are not reported to the police and also give a more reliable picture of trends, as they are not affected by changes in levels of reporting to the police or by variations in police recording practice (see Appendix, Part 9: Types of offence in England and Wales, in Scotland, and in Northern Ireland). Recorded crime data cover offences reported to, and recorded by, the police. The National Crime Recording Standard (NCRS), introduced in England and Wales in 2002 and the Scottish Crime Recording Standard (SCRS), introduced in 2004, were implemented with the aim of taking a more victim-centred approach and providing consistency between police forces (see Appendix, Part 9: National Crime Recording Standard). Police-recorded crime and survey-measured crime have different coverage. Unlike crime data recorded by the police, surveys are generally restricted to crimes against adults living in private households and their property and do not include some types of crime (for example, fraud, murder and victimless crimes such as drug use, where there is not a direct victim). See also Appendix, Part 9: Availability and comparability of data from constituent countries Table 9.1 Crimes recorded by the police: by type of offence,1 2008/09 United Kingdom Percentages England & Wales Scotland Northern Ireland Theft and handling stolen goods 36 34 24 Theft from vehicles 8 4 3 Theft of vehicles 3 3 3 Criminal damage 20 29 26 Violence against the person2 19 3 27 Burglary 12 7 11 Drugs offences 5 11 3 Fraud and forgery 3 2 3 Robbery 2 1 1 Sexual offences 1 1 2 Other offences3 2 12 3 All notifiable offences (=100%) (thousands) 4,702 377 110 1 See Appendix, Part 9: Types of offences in England and Wales, in Scotland and in Northern Ireland, and Availability and comparability of data from constituent countries. 2 Data for Scotland are serious assaults only. Those for England and Wales and Northern Ireland are all assaults including those that cause no physical injury. 3 Northern Ireland includes ‘offences against the state’. Scotland excludes ‘offending while on bail’. Source: Home Office; Scottish Government; Police Service of Northern Ireland www.statistics.gov.uk/downloads/theme_social/Social-Trends40/09_01.xls 127 Social Trends 40: 2010 edition Chapter 9: Crime and justice 9 In Scotland the term ‘crime’ is reserved for the more serious offences, broadly equivalent to ‘indictable’ and ‘triable-either- way’ offences in England and Wales, while less serious crimes are called ‘offences’ (see Appendix, Part 9: Types of offences in England and Wales, in Scotland and Northern Ireland). The most common recorded crime in Scotland in 2008/09 was theft and handling stolen goods (34 per cent), followed by criminal damage (29 per cent) and drugs offences (11 per cent). The British Crime Survey (BCS) estimates of crime are considerably higher than the number of crimes recorded by the police. Many crimes reported to the BCS are not reported to the police, for a variety of reasons. For example, people may consider that the crime was too trivial, or that it was not worthwhile reporting because there was no loss involved. Whether or not a crime had been reported to the police varies by type of offence. Of the comparable crimes covered in both the BCS and police records, (see Appendix, Part 9: Comparable crimes) in 2008/09 theft of a vehicle was the most likely crime captured in the BCS to be reported to the police: 89 per cent of all thefts of vehicles in England and Wales had been reported. Burglaries in which something was stolen had the second highest reporting rate (83 per cent). This is at least in part because both these types of crime need to be reported to the police if the victim wishes to make an insurance claim. Of the 10.7 million crimes reported to the British Crime Survey (BCS) in England and Wales in 2008/09, almost two-thirds (6.8 million offences) were household crimes (Table 9.2). The remainder, 3.9 million offences, were personal crimes. The total number of crimes estimated by the BCS rose steadily throughout the 1980s and early 1990s and peaked in 1995, at 19.4 million. Estimated crime levels then declined steadily until 2004/05 and have remained broadly stable since. The Scottish Crime and Justice Survey (SCJS) estimated that around 1.04 million crimes were committed against adults in private households in Scotland in the 12 months prior to interview in 2008/09, 70 per cent of which were property crimes. The remaining crimes were violent crimes of assault and robbery. Estimates from the Northern Ireland Crime Survey (NICS) estimated that 176,000 crimes were committed against adults living in private households in the 12 months prior to interview in 2008/09. This was a fall of almost 12 per cent compared with the total of 199,000 in 2007/08, and was two-fifths (40 per cent) lower than the peak recorded in 2003/04 (295,000 crimes). Offences and victims According to the 2008/09 British Crime Survey (BCS), around 23 per cent of all adults aged 16 and over in England and Wales had experienced one or more BCS crimes in the 12 months prior to interview. The most common crime experienced was vandalism, with 2.8 million incidents in the 12 months prior to interview (Table 9.3 overleaf). There were 1.5 million incidents of vehicle-related theft (including theft of, or from, motor vehicles, but not bicycles), a fall of two-thirds (66 per cent) since 1995. In 2008/09, vehicle-related thefts accounted for 14 per cent of BCS crime, compared with 23 per cent in 1995. In Northern Ireland in 2008/09, around 13 per cent of households were victims of at least one Northern Ireland Crime Survey (NICS) crime during the 12 months prior to interview, which is the lowest level of victimisation since the survey began in 1994/95. In Scotland in 2008/09, 20 per cent of adults were the victim of at least one Scottish Crime and Justice Survey (SCJS) crime during the 12 months prior to interview. Being a victim of crime can be traumatic and the impact can vary depending on the type of offence and the circumstances under which it occurs. For example, the impact can be worse when a person is repeatedly victimised. In the BCS, repeat victimisation is defined as being a victim of the same offence, or group of offences, more than once within a 12 month period. According to the BCS in England and Wales in 2008/09, 9 per cent of victims who experienced theft from the person in Table 9.2 British Crime Survey offences1 England & Wales Millions All household crime All personal crime All BCS crime 1983 7.7 4.2 11.9 1987 9.0 4.4 13.4 1991 10.4 4.7 15.1 1995 12.4 6.9 19.4 1999 9.4 5.6 15.0 2003/04 7.2 4.5 11.7 2007/08 6.5 3.8 10.2 2008/09 6.8 3.9 10.7 1 Until 2000 respondents were asked to recall their experience of crime in the previous calendar year. From 2001/02 onwards the British Crime Survey (BCS) became a continuous survey and the recall period was changed to the 12 months prior to interview. Source: British Crime Survey, Home Office www.statistics.gov.uk/downloads/theme_social/Social-Trends40/09_02.xls 128 Chapter 9: Crime and justice Social Trends 40: 2010 edition 9 the 12 months prior to interview had been victims of this offence more than once during the period (Figure 9.4). Victims of domestic violence were most likely to report being a repeat victim, with 38 per cent of domestic violence victims experiencing this crime more than once in the 12 months prior to interview, and around a fifth (21 per cent) were victimised at least three times. The second most common offence reported by the same victim on more than one occasion within the last 12 months was vandalism (28 per cent). In England and Wales there were 2.1 million violent offences reported in the BCS in 2008/09, a fall of 614,000 incidents since 2001/02. Assault without injury accounted for the largest proportion of violent offences (40 per cent) followed by assault with minor injury (25 per cent), wounding (22 per cent) and robbery (13 per cent). These proportions were very similar to those in 2007/08. The number of violent crimes increased during the 1980s to reach a peak of more than 4 million incidents by 1995. Incidents of BCS violent crime have fallen markedly since the mid-1990s to a level similar to 1981 (2.1 million crimes). The risk of becoming a victim of violent crime varies according to personal characteristics. Except in cases of domestic violence, men are most likely to be victims of violent crime. In England and Wales in 2008/09, the overall risk of an adult becoming a victim of violent crime at least once in the 12 months prior to interview was 3.2 per cent (Figure 9.5). This proportion rose to 13.2 per cent for men aged 16 to 24, compared with 5.5 per cent of women of the same age. The risk to a single person of becoming a victim of violence (7.6 per cent) was more than five times higher than the risk to a married person (1.4 per cent) and around twice as high as the risk to a cohabiting person (3.8 per cent) or a divorced person (3.2 per cent). The level of risk is also related to lifestyle. For example, those who visited a nightclub on average at least once a week were considerably more at risk (12.4 per cent) than those who had not visited a nightclub in the last month (2.5 per cent). Firearms are defined as having been used in an incident if they are fired, used as a blunt instrument against a person, or used as a threat. The number of reported crimes in England and Wales involving the use of a firearm was 14,250 in 2008/09, Table 9.3 Incidents of crime: by type of offence1 England & Wales Millions 1981 1991 1995 2001/02 2006/07 2007/08 2008/09 Household crime Vandalism 2.7 2.8 3.4 2.6 3.0 2.7 2.8 All vehicle-related theft2 1.8 3.8 4.4 2.5 1.7 1.5 1.5 Burglary 0.7 1.4 1.8 1.0 0.7 0.7 0.7 Bicycle theft 0.2 0.6 0.7 0.4 0.5 0.4 0.5 Other household theft3 1.5 1.9 2.3 1.4 1.2 1.1 1.2 All household crime 6.9 10.4 12.4 7.9 7.1 6.5 6.8 Personal crime Theft from the person 0.4 0.4 0.7 0.6 0.6 0.6 0.7 Other thefts of personal property 1.6 1.7 2.1 1.4 1.1 1.0 1.1 All BCS violence 2.1 2.6 4.2 2.7 2.5 2.2 2.1 Assault with minor injury 0.6 0.8 1.4 0.7 0.6 0.5 0.5 Assault with no injury 0.8 1.0 1.6 1.0 1.0 0.9 0.8 Wounding 0.5 0.6 0.9 0.6 0.6 0.5 0.5 Robbery 0.2 0.2 0.3 0.4 0.3 0.3 0.3 All personal crime 4.1 4.7 6.9 4.7 4.2 3.8 3.9 All crimes reported to BCS 11.0 15.1 19.4 12.6 11.3 10.2 10.7 1 Until 2000 respondents were asked to recall their experience of crime in the previous calendar year. From 2001/02 onwards the British Crime Survey (BCS) became a continuous survey and the recall period was changed to the 12 months prior to interview. 2 Includes theft of, or from, a vehicle, as well as attempts. 3 Includes thefts and attempted thefts from domestic garages, outhouses and sheds, not directly linked to the dwelling, as well as thefts from both inside and outside a dwelling. Source: British Crime Survey, Home Office www.statistics.gov.uk/downloads/theme_social/Social-Trends40/09_03.xls 129 Social Trends 40: 2010 edition Chapter 9: Crime and justice 9 a decrease of 18 per cent from the previous year, 2007/08, when 17,343 offences were recorded, and a fall of 41 per cent since the peak of 24,094 offences recorded in 2003/04 (Figure 9.6). In 2008/09, 8,208 offences were committed in which firearms were reported to have been used (excluding air weapons) of which 2,671 were fired with 39 offences resulting in a fatal injury. During the same period, of the total number of firearm offences (excluding air weapons) committed, 5,337 offences were reported in which the weapon was not fired but was used as a blunt instrument or to threaten a person. The number of firearm offences (excluding air weapons) involving any kind of injury almost halved between 2007/08 and 2008/09, falling from 3,241 to 1,764. An air weapon differs from the conventional firearm by the fact that it, and the pellets discharged, do not contain any explosive substance and most are of such limited powers that they are not required to be licensed, except those classified as dangerous weapons by the Firearms Rules 1969. In 2008/09, the number of reported crimes in England and Wales involving the use of an air weapon was 6,042, of which 5,340 reported incidents involved the air weapon being fired and 702 incidents were reported in which the air weapon was not fired but was used as a blunt instrument or to threaten a person. Around half of firearm offences in 2008/09 (excluding those involving air weapons) involved a handgun (52 per cent). Imitation firearms were used in 18 per cent of incidents, shotguns in 8 per cent, and rifles in 1 per cent. Other firearms including CS gas, stun guns, and paintball guns accounted for 9 per cent of all firearm offences. The firearm was unidentified in 12 per cent of offences. Table 9.3 showed that there were 1.5 million vehicle-related thefts against the household population in England and Wales in 2008/09. Of these, 70 per cent of offences were thefts from Figure 9.4 Repeat victimisation:1 by type of offence, 2008/09 England & Wales Percentages 1 Victims of the same offence, or group of offences, more than once in the last 12 months. 2 Includes thefts and attempted thefts from domestic garages, outhouses and sheds, not directly linked to the dwelling, as well as thefts from both inside and outside a dwelling. 3 Includes theft of, or from, a vehicle, as well as attempts. Source: British Crime Survey, Home Office 0 5 10 15 20 25 30 35 40 Domestic violence Vandalism Acquaintance violence Other household theft2 Vehicle-related theft3 Stranger violence Burglary Bicycle theft Other theft of personal property Theft from the person Figure 9.5 Adults most at risk of violence,1 2008/09 England & Wales Percentages 1 People who reported being a victim of violence one or more times in the 12 months prior to interview. Source: British Crime Survey, Home Office 0 2 4 6 8 10 12 14 Men aged 16–24 Visited nightclub/disco once a week or more in last month Full-time student Unemployed Single people Mixed ethnicity All adults Figure 9.6 Crimes1 reported to the police in which a firearm had been used England & Wales Thousands 1 Changes in counting offences were made in April 1998 and the National Crime Recording Standard was implemented in April 2002. See Appendix, Part 9: National Crime Recording Standard. Source: Home Office 0 5 10 15 20 25 1998/99 2000/01 2002/03 2004/05 2006/07 2008/09 Air weapons All weapons excluding air weapons All weapons www.statistics.gov.uk/downloads/theme_social/Social-Trends40/09_04.xls www.statistics.gov.uk/downloads/theme_social/Social-Trends40/09_05.xls www.statistics.gov.uk/downloads/theme_social/Social-Trends40/09_06.xls 130 Chapter 9: Crime and justice Social Trends 40: 2010 edition 9 vehicles and 10 per cent were thefts of vehicles, while 20 per cent were attempted thefts either from or of the vehicle (Figure 9.7). In a pattern similar to violent crime, the number of offences in each of the vehicle-related theft categories had fallen by around two-thirds since they peaked in 1995 (see Table 9.3). The fall in vehicle-related crime may be at least in part the result of better vehicle security. The proportion of vehicles in England and Wales fitted with security devices has risen over time and in 2008/09 the majority of vehicles had some form of security device installed: 91 per cent of main cars (that is, the car most used by the household) had central locking, and 80 per cent had immobilisers. The risk of being a victim of vehicle-related theft varies according to the employment status of the household reference person (see Reference persons text box on page 15). For example, in England and Wales in 2008/09, 10.1 per cent of households headed by a student had experienced vehicle-related theft, compared with 2.5 per cent of households headed by a retired person. The household’s accommodation was also a risk factor: households living in flats or maisonettes were more likely to be victims of vehicle-related theft (8.3 per cent) than those living in detached houses (4.7 per cent). The risk to households with three or more cars (11.1 per cent) was more than double the risk to households with only one car (5.1 per cent). In 2008, the value of transactions resulting from fraudulent use of UK credit and debit cards, both in the UK and overseas, totalled £609.9 million, an increase of 14 per cent on the previous year and over 350 per cent since 1998 (Figure 9.8). However, this amounted to 0.1 per cent of the total value of transactions made in 2008 using plastic cards issued in the UK. Losses of £379.7 million (62 per cent) occurred in the UK, compared with £230.1 million (38 per cent) of fraud which occurred abroad. More than half (54 per cent) of all losses on UK issued cards were through card-not-present transactions, and more than a quarter (28 per cent) resulted from the use of counterfeit cards. The remaining losses were a result of lost or stolen cards (9 per cent), card identity theft (8 per cent) and mail non-receipt, in which cards are stolen while in transit from the issuer to the cardholder (2 per cent). Card-not-present fraud, where genuine card details are used to make a purchase online, over the phone or by post, increased by 350 per cent between 2000 (72.9 million frauds) and 2008 (328.4 million frauds). However, over the same period, the value of online shopping alone increased more than tenfold, from £3.5 billion in 2000 to £41.2 billion in 2008. Counterfeit card fraud involves the unauthorised use of card details taken from the magnetic strip of a genuine card. Although the value of this type of card fraud taking place in UK increased by 9 per cent between 2007 and 2008, it fell by 68 per cent between 2004 and 2008 because of the introduction of chip and PIN, which requires people to enter a unique code, rather than signing their name, when purchasing goods. Counterfeit card fraud accounted for 58 per cent of losses in value that occurred abroad involving UK issued cards, as fraudsters use the cards in countries that do not yet have chip and PIN. Figure 9.7 Vehicle-related theft1 England & Wales Incidents 1 Until 2000 respondents were asked to recall their experience of crime in the previous calendar year. From 2001/02 onwards the British Crime Survey became a continuous survey and the recall period was changed to the 12 months prior to interview. Source: British Crime Survey, Home Office 0 500 1,000 1,500 2,000 2,500 1981 1991 2001/02 2008/09 Theft from vehicle Theft of vehicle Attempted theft Figure 9.8 Plastic card fraud losses1 on UK-issued cards £ million 1 Value of transactions resulting from fraudulent use of UK credit and debit cards, both in the UK and overseas. Source: The UK Cards Association 0 100 200 300 400 500 600 700 1998 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 2008 www.statistics.gov.uk/downloads/theme_social/Social-Trends40/09_07.xls www.statistics.gov.uk/downloads/theme_social/Social-Trends40/09_08.xls 131 Social Trends 40: 2010 edition Chapter 9: Crime and justice 9 Perceptions of crime Table 9.2 showed that there were an estimated 10.7 million crimes committed in England and Wales in 2008/09, a fall of 45 per cent since the peak of 19.4 million crimes recorded in 1995. However, when asked if they believed crime levels had changed nationally and locally over the last two years, the 2008/09 British Crime Survey (BCS) reported that 75 per cent of respondents thought that crime levels across the whole country had increased over the last two years, but around half this proportion (36 per cent) thought that there was more crime in their local area. This pattern of belief that crime had increased to a much greater extent nationally than in their local area was reflected in perceptions of the levels of individual types of crime. Almost four-fifths (78 per cent) of people living in private households in England and Wales in 2008/09 believed that knife crime had increased a lot nationally over the last two years, while 16 per cent thought it had increased a little (Table 9.9). At a local level, 8 per cent of people believed that knife crime had increased a lot and 21 per cent thought that it had increased a little. In contrast, BCS data show that knives were used in less than 8 per cent of all violent crimes in each year since 1995 (7 per cent in 2008/09). Bank and credit card fraud were perceived to have gone up at a local level more than any other crime, with 22 per cent of people questioned stating that they thought bank and credit card fraud had gone up a lot in their area and 31 per cent thinking that it had gone up a little. The Crime and Disorder Act (1998) defined anti-social behaviour as ‘acting in a manner that caused or was likely to cause harassment, alarm or distress, to one or more persons not of the same household (as the defendant)’. In 2008/09, 17 per cent of people questioned in England and Wales believed that there were high levels of anti-social behaviour in their area (Table 9.10). The most common anti-social behaviours Table 9.9 Perceptions of changing crime levels: by type of crime,1 2008/09 England & Wales Percentages National level Local level Increased a lot Increased a little Increased a lot Increased a little Knife crime 78 16 8 21 Bank/credit card fraud 70 21 22 31 Gun crime 62 25 4 12 People getting beaten up 55 29 9 25 Muggings/street robberies 45 34 7 23 Vandalism 40 33 9 28 Homes being broken into 31 34 9 25 Cars being broken into 34 30 9 23 Cars being stolen 31 31 6 20 1 British Crime Survey respondents were asked if they thought specific crimes had increased locally or nationally. Data are the proportion of people who answered ‘increased a lot’ or ‘increased a little’. Source: British Crime Survey, Home Office Table 9.10 Anti-social behaviour indicators1,2,3 England & Wales Percentages 1992 1996 2000 2002/03 2004/05 2006/07 2008/09 Teenagers hanging around on the streets 20 24 32 33 31 33 30 Rubbish or litter lying around 30 26 30 33 30 31 30 People using or dealing drugs 14 21 33 32 26 28 28 Vandalism, graffiti and other deliberate damage to property 26 24 32 35 28 28 27 People being drunk or rowdy in public places . . . 23 22 26 26 Noisy neighbours or loud parties 8 8 9 10 9 11 10 Abandoned or burnt-out cars4 . . 14 25 12 9 6 High level of perceived anti-social behaviour5 . . . 21 17 18 17 1 Until 2000 respondents were asked to recall their experience of crime in the previous calendar year. From 2001/02 the British Crime Survey became a continuous survey and the recall period was changed to the 12 months prior to interview. 2 People saying anti-social behaviour is a ‘very/fairly big problem’ in their area. 3 Percentages do not sum to 100 per cent as respondents could give more than one answer. 4 Question only asked of a quarter of the sample in 2002/03. 5 This measure is derived from responses to seven individual anti-social behaviour strands. See Appendix, Part 9: Anti-social behaviour indicators. Source: British Crime Survey, Home Office www.statistics.gov.uk/downloads/theme_social/Social-Trends40/09_09.xls www.statistics.gov.uk/downloads/theme_social/Social-Trends40/09_10.xls 132 Chapter 9: Crime and justice Social Trends 40: 2010 edition 9 identified were teenagers hanging around on the streets and rubbish or litter lying around, both reported by 30 per cent of survey respondents, followed by people using or dealing drugs (28 per cent); vandalism, graffiti and other deliberate damage to property (27 per cent); and people being drunk or rowdy in public (26 per cent). Between 2002/03 and 2008/09, the proportion of people who perceived abandoned or burned out cars to be a problem fell from 25 per cent to 6 per cent. Perceived levels of anti-social behaviour varied according to household and area characteristics, age and sex. For example, 19 per cent of households in urban areas felt there to be a high level of anti-social behaviour in their area compared with 8 per cent of households in rural areas. People in social rented accommodation perceived higher levels of anti-social behaviour (29 per cent) than private renters (18 per cent) or owner- occupiers (13 per cent). Older people aged 65 and over (13 per cent) were less likely to feel that there was a high level of anti-social behaviour in their area compared to young people aged 16 to 24 (24 per cent). Young women were the most likely to feel that there was a high level of anti-social behaviour in their area: 29 per cent of women aged 16 to 24 compared with 20 per cent of men in the same age group. The gap between the sexes narrowed in the older age groups and at the oldest ages there was no difference: 9 per cent of both men and women aged 65 to 74 and 4 per cent of both men and women aged 75 and over felt there was a high level of anti-social behaviour problems in their area. Offenders Recorded crime figures based on administrative data collected by the police show that in 2008, 1.69 million offenders were found guilty of, or cautioned for, indictable and summary (including motoring) offences in England and Wales. (See Appendix, Part 9: Types of offence in England and Wales). Most of the offenders were male (76 per cent), of whom around 11 per cent were aged under 18. In 2008, 32,700 people aged 10 to 14 were found guilty of, or cautioned for, an indictable offence in England and Wales. Males in this age group were more likely than females to be offenders, 22,200 compared with 10,500 (Figure 9.11). Of all offenders who were found guilty of, or cautioned for, an indictable offence in 2008, 35 per cent were aged 20 to 29, the highest proportion for any age group. The proportion of the population who were offenders declined with age as males and females entered their 30s. Less than 15 per cent of males and females over the age of 40 were found guilty of, or cautioned for, an indictable offence in 2008. For those aged 60 and over the proportion of the population who were offenders was negligible. In Northern Ireland, 7,600 offenders were found guilty of, or cautioned for, indictable offences in 2006. Of these, 88 per cent were male. Young men aged 19 and 20 were most likely to be offenders, with 4 per cent of this age group being found guilty of, or cautioned for, an indictable offence. The proportion of women who were offenders was less than 1 per cent for all age groups. The type of indictable offences for which people were found guilty of, or cautioned for, were similar for men and women in England and Wales in 2008. For both men and women, the most common indictable offence was theft and handling stolen goods accounting for 31 per cent of all male offences (125,200) and 52 per cent of all female offences (48,900) (Figure 9.12). The second most common offences for men were drug offences (88,800) at 22 per cent followed by violence against the person (65,100) at 16 per cent of all male offences. Theft and handling stolen goods, violence against the person and drug offences accounted for the majority of all offences by females (78 per cent). ‘Other offences’, which include fraud and forgery and indictable motoring offences, accounted for 16 per cent of offences for both men and women. In Northern Ireland, the most common offences to be found guilty of, or cautioned for, in 2006 were violent offences (violence against a person, sexual offences, and robbery) and acquisitive offences (theft, burglary and fraud and forgery) Figure 9.11 Offenders:1,2,3 by age England & Wales Thousands 1 People found guilty of, or cautioned for, indictable offences. 2 For motoring offences only persons found guilty are included; these offences may attract written warnings, which are not included in this chart. 3 Data for April, July and August 2008 excludes convictions data for Cardiff magistrates’ court. Source: Office for Criminal Justice Reform, Ministry of Justice 0 40 80 120 160 200 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 2008 10–19 20–29 30–39 40–49 50–59 60 and over www.statistics.gov.uk/downloads/theme_social/Social-Trends40/09_11.xls 133 Social Trends 40: 2010 edition Chapter 9: Crime and justice 9 both at 34 per cent, followed by criminal damage and drug related offences, at 17 per cent and 10 per cent respectively. Not all offences have to be dealt with by the court, the police can deal with some people using a range of alternatives such as a simple caution, conditional caution, penalty notice for disorder or fixed penalty notice for motoring offences. Once the police obtain enough evidence for conviction, the offenders are charged and taken to court where, if found guilty, the court imposes a sentence. Sentences in England, Wales and Northern Ireland can include immediate custody, a community sentence, a fine or, if the court considers that no punishment is necessary, a discharge. In 2008, of the 495,200 offenders found guilty of, or cautioned for, indictable offences in England and Wales, 63 per cent (310,000 offenders) were sentenced (Table 9.13). The type of sentence given depends on the offence committed and other factors that may be applied on a case-by-case basis (see Appendix, Part 9: Sentences and orders). In 2008, the most common type of sentence was a community sentence (32 per cent), with more than two-fifths (44 per cent) of offenders sentenced for criminal damage receiving this sentence. Suspended sentence order was the least common sentence given at 9 per cent, with violence against a person and motoring offenders being the most likely offenders (18 per cent) to receive this sentence. Figure 9.12 Offenders found guilty of, or cautioned for, indictable offences:1 by sex and type of offence, 2008 England & Wales Thousands 1 See Appendix, Part 9: Types of offence in England and Wales. 2 Includes fraud and forgery and indictable motoring offences. Source: Office for Criminal Justice Reform, Ministry of Justice Theft and handling stolen goods Drug offences Violence against the person Burglary Criminal damage Robbery Sexual offences Other offences2 0 15 30 45 60 75 90 105 120 135 Males Females Table 9.13 Offenders sentenced for indictable offences: by type of offence1 and type of sentence,2 2008 England & Wales Percentages Discharge Fine Community sentence Suspended sentence order Immediate custody Other All sentenced (=100%) (thousands) Theft and handling stolen goods 20 13 37 6 19 6 109.5 Drug offences 16 33 23 6 18 4 52.4 Violence against the person 5 4 36 18 33 4 39.8 Burglary 3 2 40 10 42 4 23.6 Fraud and forgery 14 12 28 15 30 3 16.9 Criminal damage 21 11 44 5 12 8 9.4 Motoring 3 20 27 18 30 2 4.6 Robbery 0 0 34 5 60 2 8.5 Sexual offences 3 2 27 8 58 2 5.1 Other offences 9 28 23 10 24 7 40.3 All indictable offences 13 16 32 9 25 5 310.0 1 See Appendix, Part 9: Types of offence in England and Wales. 2 Data are based on the principle offence basis, where an offender has been sentenced for more than one offence the principle offence is the one for which the heaviest sentence was imposed. See Appendix, Part 9: Sentences and orders. Source: Ministry of Justice www.statistics.gov.uk/downloads/theme_social/Social-Trends40/09_12.xls www.statistics.gov.uk/downloads/theme_social/Social-Trends40/09_13.xls 134 Chapter 9: Crime and justice Social Trends 40: 2010 edition 9 Prisons and sentencing Prison is the usual eventual destination for offenders given custodial sentences, and also for those who break the terms of their non-custodial sentence. Sentenced prisoners are classified into different risk-level groups for security purposes. Women prisoners are held in separate prisons or in separate accommodation in mixed prisons. Young offenders receiving custodial sentences have traditionally been separated from adult offenders, enabling them to receive additional educational and rehabilitative treatment. The size of the prison population in England and Wales (those held in prison but excluding those in police cells, see Appendix, Part 9: Prison population for more details) has risen by 79 per cent over the years from 17,435 in 1900 when the records began to reach 82,572 in 2008. During this period the population of females in prisons almost doubled from 2,976 in 1900 to 4,414 in 2008, but decreased as a proportion of the male population from 17 per cent in 1900 to 5 per cent in 2008 (Figure 9.14). The prison population was relatively stable during the 1970s and early 1990s, but in the mid-1990s it began to increase. The largest increase during the 1990s occurred between 1996 and 1997 at 11 per cent. Apart from decreases of less than 1 per cent in 1993 and again in 1999, the prison population has increased annually since 1991. Of the 70,800 British nationals in prison in England and Wales in 2008, the majority were White (79 per cent of male inmates and 83 per cent of female inmates) (Table 9.15). The second largest ethnic group within the prison population in 2008 was Black or Black British, at 11 per cent of male inmates and 9 per cent of female inmates. The proportions of male and female inmates who were from the Mixed ethnic group were similar (3 per cent and 4 per cent respectively) but there were more Asian or Asian British males in prison (5 per cent of all inmates) than Asian or Asian British females (2 per cent). On 30 June 2009 the prison population was 83,454, with a further 258 people held in secure training centres and 175 in local authority children’s homes, an increase in total prison population of less than 1 per cent compared with June 2008. The increased prison population may partly result from a rise in the use of longer prison sentences. Average custodial sentence lengths given by the Crown court have increased from 21.8 months in 1998 to 24.5 months in 2008. Over the same period, the average length of custodial sentences given by the magistrates’ courts has been stable at around three months. In 2007, there were 2.7 million motoring offences in England and Wales dealt with by official police action or penalty notice charge, of which 2.6 million were fixed penalty notices issued by the police (including traffic wardens) which were paid and thus resulted in no further action. Speed and traffic light cameras in England and Wales provided evidence for almost Figure 9.14 Average prison population:1,2 by sex England & Wales Thousands 1 Data are annual averages. 2 Excludes prisoners held in police cells. Source: Ministry of Justice 0 10 20 30 40 50 60 70 Males Females 80 1968 1973 1978 1983 1988 1993 1998 2003 2008 Table 9.15 Prison population of British nationals: by ethnic group1 England & Wales Percentages 2004 2005 2006 2007 2008 Males White 75 82 81 80 79 Mixed 2 3 3 3 3 Asian or Asian British 4 5 5 5 5 Black or Black British 9 10 11 11 11 Chinese and other ethnic group - - - - - Total male population (=100%) (thousands) 60.8 62.1 62.7 64.5 67.3 Females White 78 82 83 84 83 Mixed 4 5 4 4 4 Asian or Asian British 1 2 2 2 2 Black or Black British 9 10 10 9 9 Chinese and other ethnic group - - - - - Total female population (=100%) (thousands) 3.6 3.5 3.4 3.2 3.5 1 See Appendix, Part 1: Classification of ethnic groups. Source: Ministry of Justice www.statistics.gov.uk/downloads/theme_social/Social-Trends40/09_14.xls www.statistics.gov.uk/downloads/theme_social/Social-Trends40/09_15.xls 135 Social Trends 40: 2010 edition Chapter 9: Crime and justice 9 1.4 million of these fixed penalties, an increase of nearly half (48 per cent) compared with 2001 (Table 9.16). The majority (92 per cent) of those offences for which evidence had been provided by a camera were speeding offences, with the remainder being traffic light offences. Overall, cameras were used to provide evidence for 86 per cent of speeding offences in 2007 that resulted in fixed penalty notices being issued. Cameras were also used in 53 per cent of offences of neglect of traffic signs and directions and pedestrian rights, which includes traffic light offences. Fixed penalty notices are motoring offences that are issued on the spot, and can be endorsable (accompanied by points added on the driving licence) or non-endorsable (no points added). There was a fall in the number of fixed penalty notices issued in England and Wales for the use of a hand-held mobile phone while driving, from 167,000 offences in 2006 to 122,000 offences in 2007. This is partly because, at the end of February 2007, the offence was changed from a non-endorsable offence to an endorsable offence, increasing the penalty and adding points to the offender’s licence. In 2007, 90 per cent of fixed penalty notices issued by the police were paid. Fixed penalty notices issued for endorsable offences were more likely to be paid without further enforcement action than were those for non-endorsable offences: 98 per cent of fixed penalty notices issued for endorsable offences were paid compared with 74 per cent of non-endorsable offences where the driver was present and 73 per cent of non-endorsable offences where the driver was not present. Anti-social behaviour orders (ASBOs) were introduced in England and Wales under the Crime and Disorder Act (1998) and have been available since April 1999. ASBOs are civil orders that impose restrictions on the behaviour of individuals who have behaved in an anti-social way in order to protect communities from often longstanding and intimidating activity. They can be made against anyone aged 10 and over. The number of ASBOs issued in England and Wales increased from 350 in 2001 to a peak of 4,122 in 2005, since when they have fallen back to 2,299 in 2007. The increase between 2003 and 2005 followed the introduction of the Anti-Social Behaviour Act in 2003. This Act strengthened the ASBO by increasing the number of categories for which ASBOs can be awarded, enhancing their legal status and banning spray paint sales to people under the age of 16, and also gave local councils the power to order the removal of graffiti from private property. It also covers truancy, people making false reports of emergency, misuse of fireworks, private drunkenness and gang activity. Of the 2,299 ASBOs issued in 2007, 17 ASBOs were to persons of unknown age. Of the 2,282 ASBOs issued to persons of known age 1,362 were issued to individuals aged 18 and over, and 920 were issued to 10 to 17-year-olds (Figure 9.17). A larger proportion of males than females were issued ASBOs in 2007. Of the total number of ASBOs issued in this year, half (50 per cent) were issued to men aged 18 and over and more than a third (36 per cent) were issued to males aged 10 to 17, while 9 per cent were issued to women aged 18 and over and 4 per cent were issued to females aged 10 to 17. The remaining 1 per cent were issued to males whose age was unknown. Table 9.16 Fixed penalties1 for motoring offences detected by cameras: by type of offence England & Wales Thousands Speeding offences Traffic light offences All offences 2001 878 46 923 2002 1,135 71 1,206 2003 1,670 115 1,785 2004 1,787 113 1,900 2005 1,764 123 1,887 2006 1,634 119 1,752 2007 1,260 109 1,369 1 Includes paid, fixed penalties only. Offences where the fixed penalty was not paid are not counted, as further action was taken. Source: Home Office 1 Issued at all HM Courts and reported to the Home Office by the Courts Service. Source: Home Office Figure 9.17 Number of anti-social behaviour orders (ASBOs) issued:1 by age England & Wales Numbers 0 500 1,000 1,500 2,000 2,500 3,000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 10–17 18 and over www.statistics.gov.uk/downloads/theme_social/Social-Trends40/09_16.xls www.statistics.gov.uk/downloads/theme_social/Social-Trends40/09_17.xls 136 Chapter 9: Crime and justice Social Trends 40: 2010 edition 9 Between June 2000 and December 2007 a total of 14,972 ASBOs were issued in England and Wales. Of these, more than half (53 per cent) were proved in court to have been breached at least once and 39 per cent were proved to have been breached more than once. Life imprisonment, or its equivalent, must be imposed on all persons aged 10 and over convicted of murder. This sentence may also be imposed for a number of the most serious crimes, including manslaughter, robbery, rape, assault with intent to do grievous bodily harm, aggravated burglary, and certain firearms offences. In 2008, 523 people were sentenced to life imprisonment in England and Wales, a fall of 4 per cent compared with 2006 (Table 9.18). The great majority of people sentenced to life imprisonment were men (95 per cent) and just over one in ten (11 per cent) were aged 18 to 20 and one in twenty (almost 5 per cent) were males aged 10 to 17. In Scotland, 32 people were sentenced to life imprisonment in 2008, excluding those given indeterminate sentences. This was a decrease of 21 persons on the previous year. More than three-quarters (78 per cent) were men aged 21 and over, and 19 per cent were men aged 18 to 20. No life sentences have been issued to anyone aged under 18 in Scotland since 2004. Resources There were 43 police forces in England and Wales employing 143,770 full-time equivalent police officers at 31 March 2009, the highest number of police officers ever recorded. Of these, 6,290 police officers were from an ethnic minority group, equivalent to 4.4 per cent of the total police strength and double the proportion recorded in 2000 (2.2 per cent) (Table 9.19). The proportion of police officers belonging to an ethnic minority was lower at senior ranks. In 2009, 2.8 per cent of officers at chief superintendent level were from an ethnic minority compared with 4.8 per cent of officers who were constables. One per cent of officers did not state their ethnicity in 2009. Of the officers who stated they were from an ethnic minority group, 39.3 per cent were Asian or Asian British, 27.0 per cent were from the Mixed ethnic group, 22.7 per cent were Black or Black British and 11.0 per cent were from the Chinese or Other ethnic group. The proportion of ethnic minority officers varies by police force in England and Wales. The largest proportion of ethnic minority officers were based in the Metropolitan Police force (8.8 per cent) which accounted for 45 per cent of all ethnic minority police officers in England and Wales, followed by West Midlands (7.7 per cent), accounting for 11 per cent, Leicestershire (6.6 per cent) accounting for 2 per cent and Bedfordshire (6.1 per cent) accounting for 1 per cent. Police officers from ethnic minority groups accounted for less than 1 per cent of the total police strength in four police force areas in 2009: North Wales (0.8 per cent), Devon and Cornwall (0.8 per cent), Dyfed Powys (0.7 per cent) and Humberside (0.9 per cent). A quarter (25.1 per cent) of all police officers in England and Wales were women at 31 March 2009. This proportion was lower in the more senior ranks with 13.0 per cent of officers at rank of chief inspector or above being female compared with 27.9 per cent who were constables. According to the 2008/09 British Crime Survey just over two-thirds (67 per cent) of people in England and Wales had overall confidence in the police in their local area, a Table 9.18 People sentenced to life imprisonment:1 by sex England & Wales Numbers Males Females All people 1998 380 14 394 2000 446 21 467 2002 536 19 555 2004 548 22 570 2006 531 16 547 2008 495 28 523 1 See Appendix, Part 9: Sentences and orders. Source: Ministry of Justice Table 9.19 Ethnic1 minority police officers as a proportion of all police officers: by rank2 England & Wales Percentages 2008 2009 Association of Chief Police Officers 3.3 4.0 Chief Superintendents 2.3 2.8 Superintendents 2.9 3.2 Chief Inspectors 3.0 2.7 Inspectors 2.6 3.1 Sergeants 3.0 3.2 Constables 4.4 4.8 All ethnic minority police officers 4.1 4.4 1 See Appendix, Part 1: Classification of ethnic groups. 2 As at 31 March in each year. Source: Home Office www.statistics.gov.uk/downloads/theme_social/Social-Trends40/09_18.xls www.statistics.gov.uk/downloads/theme_social/Social-Trends40/09_19.xls 137 Social Trends 40: 2010 edition Chapter 9: Crime and justice 9 2 percentage point increase since 2007/08 (Table 9.20). More than half (53 per cent) of people thought that their local police force was doing a good or excellent job, the same proportion as the previous year, and a 3 percentage point increase since 2005/06. In general, these indicators showed that the majority of people in England and Wales agreed that their local police treat people with respect (84 per cent), that they treat everyone fairly (65 per cent), and that they understand the issues affecting the community (65 per cent). People were less likely to agree that their local police force could be relied upon to be there when needed (48 per cent) or to deal with minor crimes (46 per cent). The proportion of people who agreed that their local police force was doing a good or excellent job in 2008/09 varied according to certain demographic characteristics. For example, women were more inclined than men to rate the police as doing a good or excellent job (56 per cent compared with 51 per cent) and people from non-White groups were more likely than White people to rate the police as doing a good or excellent job (57 per cent compared with 53 per cent). However, 67 per cent of men thought that the police would treat people fairly, compared with 63 per cent of women. Similarly, 84 per cent of White people thought that the police would treat people with respect, compared with 81 per cent of people from non-White groups. In 2008/09, a total of 31,259 complaint cases were made by members of the public against those serving with the police in England and Wales, an increase of 8 per cent on the previous year and the most complaints recorded in a single year since 1990 (Figure 9.21). Complaints were made by 31,673 individuals in England and Wales in 2008/09, a rate of approximately one complainant per complaint. Almost two-thirds (63 per cent) of complainants were White, Table 9.20 Ratings and perceptions of local police England & Wales Percentages 2005/06 2006/07 2007/08 2008/09 Ratings of local police1 How good a job do you think the police are doing 50 51 53 53 Perceptions of police in local area2 Would treat you with respect if you had contact with them 82 83 83 84 Treat everyone fairly regardless of who they are 63 62 64 65 Understand the issues that affect this community 60 60 62 65 Are dealing with the things that matter to people in the community 49 49 51 54 Can be relied on to be there when you need them 47 47 48 48 Can be relied on to deal with minor crimes 42 41 43 46 Overall confidence in the local police2,3 63 64 65 67 1 Proportion of respondents who rated police as excellent/good. 2 Proportion of respondents who strongly agreed/tended to agree with the statement. 3 Based on the question ‘Taking everything into account I have confidence in the police in this area’. Source: British Crime Survey, Home Office Figure 9.21 Number of complaint cases recorded1,2 by police forces England & Wales Thousands 0 5 10 15 20 25 30 35 1990 1993 1996/97 1999/2000 2002/03 2005/06 2008/09 1 Complaints made by members of the public against those serving with the police. Includes completed complaint cases and pending cases at end of reporting year. 2 Data from 2004/05 are post-Police Reform Act 2002. Source: Independent Police Complaints Commission www.statistics.gov.uk/downloads/theme_social/Social-Trends40/09_20.xls www.statistics.gov.uk/downloads/theme_social/Social-Trends40/09_21.xls 138 Chapter 9: Crime and justice Social Trends 40: 2010 edition 9 7 per cent were Black, 6 per cent were Asian, 3 per cent were in the Other ethnic group and the ethnicity of around a fifth (22 per cent) of complainants was unknown. A complaint may comprise one or more allegations, for example, a person may complain that a police officer was rude to them (one complaint) or that he was rude to them and that he pushed them (two allegations but treated as one complaint). There were 53,534 allegations in England and Wales in 2008/09, a rise of 11 per cent on 2007/08. The most common types were ‘incivility, impoliteness and intolerance’ (21 per cent), which includes abusive, offensive or rude language or behaviour, and ‘other assault’ (13 per cent), which includes allegations that unreasonable force was used. Allegations of ‘other neglect or failure in duty’ (24 per cent) includes allegations such as a failure to record or investigate matters and keep interested parties informed. Allegations of discriminatory behaviour formed 3 per cent of the total, the majority of which (76 per cent) concerned allegations of racial discrimination. The British Crime Survey asked people in England and Wales how confident they were that the Criminal Justice System (CJS) was fair and effective. Overall, 59 per cent of people questioned in 2008/09 thought that the CJS was fair although fewer people (38 per cent) thought that it was effective. However, levels of confidence in the CJS, particularly in its effectiveness, vary considerably by the respondent’s occupation (Table 9.22). For example, 72 per cent of full-time students felt that the CJS was fair and 60 per cent thought that it was effective. In comparison, 56 per cent of those in intermediate or routine and manual occupations felt that the CJS was fair and 35 per cent of those in managerial and professional or intermediate occupations thought that it was effective. White people were less likely to have confidence in the CJS than people from other ethnic groups. In 2008/09, 57 per cent of White people thought that the CJS was fair and 36 per cent thought that it was effective. In comparison, 72 per cent of Asian or Asian British people thought that the CJS was fair and 61 per cent thought that it was effective. For Black and Black British people, the equivalent figures were 60 per cent and 51 per cent. People who had any type of contact with the police in the 12 months prior to interview were slightly less likely to believe that the CJS was fair (57 per cent) or effective (37 per cent) that those who had not had contact with the police (61 per cent and 40 per cent). Table 9.22 Confidence in the criminal justice system (CJS): by respondent’s occupation, 2008/09 England & Wales Percentages Confidence that the CJS is fair Confidence that the CJS is effective Managerial and professional occupations 59 35 Intermediate occupations 56 35 Routine and manual occupations 56 38 Never worked and long-term unemployed 68 52 Full-time students 72 60 Not classified 49 32 Source: British Crime Survey, Home Office www.statistics.gov.uk/downloads/theme_social/Social-Trends40/09_22.xls Crime and justice Crime levels Offences and victims Perceptions of crime Offenders Prisons and sentencing Resources work_eleckkd64rfkpbqkfltamwlwiq ---- Review Caring democracy: Markets, equality and justice Joan Tronto New York University Press, New York and London, 2013, x+228pp., ISBN: 978-0814782774 Contemporary Political Theory (2016) 15, e22–e25. doi:10.1057/cpt.2015.32; published online 2 June 2015 Don’t let ‘care’ distract you. This book is about democracy, what it requires, what troubles ours and how we might remedy contemporary political malaise. Care, Joan Tronto compellingly argues, is at the heart of both our democratic deficit and our democratic potential. Tronto leads a multidisciplinary field of scholars who have developed a rich literature on care. In this latest pioneering contribution, she brings the insights of care theory to bear on democratic theory and practice. This long-overdue connection reveals much about our political present and possible futures. With Caring Democracy Tronto contributes to renewed efforts to theorize the interaction between economic and political forces of contemporary life. The work vividly illustrates how democracy depends on activities that are often ignored, undervalued and left out of public discussions, and provides a devastating account of how gender norms, tropes of choice and personal responsibility, and market mechan- isms are deployed in the neoliberal context to undermine both care and democracy. The book is of two parts. The first is conceptual, an argument about the connections between democracy and care, and the implications for self-consistent democrats (care-ist and other); the second is a critique of current practices, rhetoric and rationality. Both are powerful and compelling. Tronto’s argument begins with that oft-forgotten fact of which she has spent her career reminding us: we human beings depend on care. ‘Care’ is a vexing political concept. Its maternalist roots suggest something women do in ‘the private sphere’. Tronto’s signature contribution is to expand our understanding of what care is and why it is an essential concern of politics and political theory. In Caring Democracy, she returns to a definition that she and Bernice Fisher developed in 1990: ‘care is a species activity that includes everything that we do to maintain, continue, and repair our “world” so that we can live in it as well as possible’ (p. 19). If this sounds like nearly everything we do, it is. Expansiveness, in a sense, is her point. It is essential to the political project of © 2016 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Vol. 15, 2, e22–e25 www.palgrave-journals.com/cpt/ http://dx.doi.org/10.1057/cpt.2015.32 http://www.palgrave-journals.com/cpt exposing and revaluing the swaths of too often ignored activity upon which our lives – and democracy – depend. We are interdependent beings. Living well is not a solo endeavor; it is the result, and Tronto would argue, the activity of care – giving, receiving, taking, sharing – broadly understood. This is the case she makes: production (for example, factory work) and societal protection (for example, policing) ought to be understood as caring activities, similar in key ways to, for example, educating, meal preparing and house cleaning (p. 21). It follows, as she shows, that the distribution of care has profound impacts on the distribution of social and political power. Receive inadequate care and one is less likely to develop the capacity to function well as a democratic citizen; shoulder too much caregiving and one is less likely to have the resources to participate in the democratic process. Call these the facts of care. What we ought to do about these facts, Tronto insists, is a political question. Indeed, as she points out, acknowledged or not, every political system and theory has an account of care and its demands (p. 28). In refreshing divergence from the dominant strains of care theory, Tronto filters the facts of care through democratic commitments. Thus she adds to her earlier definition a ‘final phase of care’: ‘caring with … requires that caring needs and the ways in which they are met need to be consistent with democratic commitments to justice, equality and freedom for all’ (p. 23). If a commitment to democracy implies a commitment to equal voice, then it also entails – at very least, Tronto argues – a commitment to making the distribution of caring responsibilities the first concern of politics. Tronto – it should be highlighted – writes as a partisan of democracy, albeit democracy defined in light of the facts of care. ‘Democratic life rests upon the presumption that citizens are equal … What is distinctive about democratic caring, though, is that it presumes … that we are equal as democratic citizens in being care receivers …. This quality of being needy is shared, equally by all humans’ (p. 29). Building from this Tronto argues that ‘[t]o be a citizen in a democracy is to care for citizens and to care for democracy itself. I call this practice “caring with” ’ (p. x). And to do this, the distribution of care needs to be the first concern of our political lives. Some will worry that she puts outcome (that is, a certain distribution of care) before democratic process. In fact, though, her position is deeply faithful to democratic process; the concern about the distribution of care stems from a commitment to what she quite plausibly claims is the defining value implicit in a commitment to democratic process, that of equal voice. Once ‘a democratic society makes a commitment to equality of all of its members, then the ways in which the inequalities of care affect different citizens’ capacities to be equal has to be a central part of the society’s political tasks’(p. 10). With the conceptual frame of a ‘feminist democratic ethic’ in hand, in the three central and perhaps best chapters of the book, Tronto turns a critical eye to contemporary life. Patriarchal gender norms, neoliberal rationality and marketization, she shows, distort the realities of care and real costs of democracy, and threaten both. Review e23© 2016 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Vol. 15, 2, e22–e25 Some citizens shoulder more care responsibilities or receive inadequate care and thus have inadequate resources to participate in politics; other more privileged citizens can purchase better care and are given ‘passes’ that exempt them from significant care responsibilities. Heteronormative masculinity underpins the ‘production’ and ‘protec- tion’ passes that exempt cis-gender men from giving care typically associated with women. Tronto’s expansive definition of care is key here. For her, both production and protection are caring activities. It is not, then, that men do not care, but that our ideologies of gender, citizenship and the private sphere obscure the ways in which care is distributed. Gender norms are also at work, she shows, where recipients of ‘nurturant’ care are cast as feminized dependents and recipients of ‘protective’ care have their status as a citizen affirmed. Gender thus links threats to care and democracy. Neoliberal practices and rationality do much the same. Tronto’s illuminating and much-needed discussion of the marketization of care calls attention to the ways in which class and race mark some as ideal caregivers and thus more likely to be assigned caring responsibilities. For others, class and race function as passes of ‘privileged irresponsibility’ that allow them to shunt caring responsibilities onto others. Neoliberal rationality also underwrites the ‘bootstrap’ and ‘charity’ passes. Representing the refrains of ‘personal responsibility’ and obligation as the results of unfettered choice respectively, both feed the conclusion that care should be left to the market. Without rejecting the value of market mechanisms altogether, Tronto makes a powerful case that this turn threatens both care and democracy. Not only do the market values of efficiency and fungible exchange conflict with the nature of key varieties of care, but markets have very bad memories; they thus tend to re-entrench social inequality and are ill-suited to relieving it. Indeed, without historical memory – and the realities of interdependence it reveals – the basis for the far-reaching sense of responsibility she advocates is lost. By effacing the facts of care, neoliberal rationality and the market mechanisms it champions threaten care and democracy. In the final two chapters, Tronto begins to paint a picture of how we might think about care democratically. Her broadly compelling account provides essential foundations for further work on how care and democracy might be harmonized. This is an important and pioneering book. Any effort of such ambition is bound to leave unanswered questions. Caring Democracy is no exception. To say, as many have, that Tronto’s definition of care is broad is close to an understatement. Indeed, it is not entirely clear what human activity would not fall into the category of care. Poetry, play, violence? Given its baggage of, for example, the connotation of altruism and the historical connection (in scholarship and practice) to motherhood and gendered labor, the question is important. Tronto’s efforts to address it – saying that the general concept can be refined for particular purposes – are successful in part but not, I think, entirely. Take, for example, the function of necessity in the concept. The language of need is central to Tronto’s discussion. Clearly, she has in mind activities that are essential – not superfluous – to living well. The normative power of this status is important: if none of us can do without care, if we have no choice but to Review e24 © 2016 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Vol. 15, 2, e22–e25 depend on the care of others, then to claim that we are in some sense mutually responsible for one another makes sense. And yet, as Hannah Arendt has argued, the introduction of necessity into political discourse has a way of closing off real deliberation. One is tempted to ask: what happens, on her account, when the demos doesn’t care about care? What if an actual democratic process does not produce the conclusions she shows are the essential to the realization of democracy’s defining values? Explicitly, Tronto sides with the democratic process. But one wonders then what to do with the force of necessity highlighted by care. To be sure, this is a vexing question for all democratic theory. The essential contribution Tronto makes here is to help us see just what is at stake, really, in our commitment to democracy. Once again, Tronto has broken new ground. The path laid here is one down which anyone interested in democratic, feminist and care theory, and our political world more generally is wise to follow. Tamara Metz Reed College, Portland, OR 97202, USA Review e25© 2016 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Vol. 15, 2, e22–e25 Caring democracy: Markets, equality and justice work_eltmx4ltfbeobodupm6erxskna ---- cover final Against Sen Against Rawls on Justice Evan Riley* Amartya Sen has recently levelled a series of what he alleges to be quite serious but very general objections against Rawls, Rawlsian fellow travellers, and other social contract accounts of justice. In The Idea of Justice, published in 2009, Sen specifically charges his target philosophical views with what he calls transcendentalism and procedural parochialism, and with being mistakenly narrowly focused on institutions. He also thinks that there is a basic incoherence—arising from a version of Derek Parfit’s Identity Problem—internal to the Rawlsian theoretical apparatus. Sen would have political philosophy pursue inter-societal comparisons of relative justice more directly and in the manner of social choice theory. Yet the positive argument that he develops in support of this method is quite thin. That aside, Sen’s polemical strategy of inflicting death by a thousand cuts is ineffective against the Rawlsian paradigm. For, as I show herein, none of these criticisms has the force we might be led to expect. Keywords: The Idea of Justice, Amartya Sen, Transendental versus Comparative justice Among his many contributions to morally engaged intellectual life, Amartya Sen has long been a trenchant and sympathetic critic of John Rawls's work.1 One of his seminal efforts in that regard is his charge that Rawls's original emphasis in A Theory of Justice on shares of primary social goods, and in particular, on the socially sanctioned all purpose means of fulfilling one’s legitimate ends— for example, monetary income and wealth—is perhaps distorted (see Sen, 1980). Recall that for Rawls therein, the primary social goods are broadly categorized as the “rights and liberties, opportunities and powers, income and wealth” that a rational representative behind the veil of ignorance is presumed to want, and to want more of, whatever else they may want.2 On Rawls' view, it is the fair distribution of these very goods that the just basic structure of society is properly concerned with. As Sen pointed out, this classification may obscure the fact that what we ought to care about in this connection is not the largest fair share of stuff as such, even such potentially useful stuff as money. Instead, the truly basic emphasis should be on fairly fostering the development of capabilities of individual human beings to realize valuable forms of functioning. It is the production and distribution of this sort of thing that properly constituted societies ought to be concerned with. This is a valuable insight, and more of a friendly emendation than a devastating criticism.3 First, by abstracting away from monetary wealth, Sen’s line of thought broadens the potential scope of the Rawlsian-style argument to naturally include more social worlds and more kinds of individual lives. Second, by placing the emphasis squarely on the realized capabilities of human beings, Sen encourages us not to distort our reflections about social justice in the direction of thinking that it is merely a matter of securing the negative liberties. I say ‘Bravo!’ to this. Indian Journal of Human Development, Vol. 5, No. 1, 2011 * Visiting Assistant Professor of Philosophy, The College of Wooster, Ohio, USA. Email: eriley@wooster.edu 212 Indian Journal of Human Development Sen has more recently been arguing for a full-scale recasting of academic philosophical theorizing about social justice.4 I think that this new line of argument is neither remotely convincing in its attack on Rawls nor insightful in its intended basic aim. In an article written in 2006, “What Do We Want from a Theory of Justice?” (see Sen, 2006), he defended this line and strikingly concluded that political philosophers should simply stop pursuing, in the style of Rawls, the grand question ‘What is a just society?’. In presumptive contrast with this dominant approach, Sen argues that political philosophers should be centrally concerned with the making of comparative judgments of justice in a way inspired by the social choice tradition and by Adam Smith, among others. This line of thinking has been redeployed, along with several other arguments that are critical of Rawls, and of the Rawlsian paradigm, in Sen’s recent book, The Idea of Justice (see Sen, 2009). Therein Sen alleges that Rawls' exhaustively discussed and enormously influential account of social justice in A Theory of Justice is vitiated by a host of very serious faults that have not been properly appreciated to date. Chief among these are transcendentalism, procedural parochialism, institutionalism, and populational plasticity. The faults are serious enough, according to Sen, to render the theory and its many relatives and descendants distinctly unhelpful as tools for “enhancing justice and removing injustice” or for serving as “the basis of practical reasoning” in that regard (see Sen, The Idea of Justice, 2009, p. ix). A new approach is recommended: call it comparativism. Here, I argue that there are basic difficulties with the critical side of this line of thought. First, it appears that either these alleged faults are not both correctly attributable to Rawls and genuine problems, or if they are genuine problems, are not specific to the Rawlsian problematic. Second, it is not clear that every such theory of justice is properly supposed to provide us with concrete plans of action for its own realization, and Sen does not make that case. Herein, I am mostly occupied with a critical discussion of the alleged problems mentioned above. I close with some very brief reflections on theories of justice and the actualization of justice. First, what is the character of the alleged problem of transcendentalism, said to be characteristic of what Sen calls “transcendental institutionalism” or in some places, the “contractarian approach” (see Sen, The Idea of Justice, 2009, pp. 5 and xvi, respectively)? Sen suggests that the Rawlsian-style pursuit of the grand question— ‘What is a just society?’—involves a pretension to extremely demanding theoretical comprehensiveness concerning its object. Indeed, Sen takes the contractarian tradition generally to be so focused on a kind of theoretical perfection that it is blocked from developing the materials for making comparative judgments of relative justice and injustice. It does seem clear that making such comparative judgments is a necessary condition of practically reasoned social reform. For in the absence of some actual comparisons, in point of justice, between say present conditions on the ground and an achievable reform, a desire to seek and support justice would be without reasoned practical import. Thus, we are invited to think that pursuing the question in a Rawlsian—or more generally contractualist—fashion will militate against realizing needed social reform. Against Sen Against Rawls on Justice 213 Two questions naturally arise. First, what exactly is the nature of the problem for the comparison posed by the relevant theoretical perfectionism? Second, is the Rawlsian framework perfectionist or transcendentalist in that sense, and is it thereby worse than useless for thinking comparatively about social justice here and now? Sen’s answer to the second question is ‘Yes’. I will take this up below and show that this is a mistaken answer. Sen’s answer to the first of these questions appears to be as follows: first, any theory that aims at completely thoroughly describing the just society and at making out an ideally complete and useful set of practical principles for realizing and maintaining justice is perfectionist (or ‘transcendental’) in the relevant sense. And, second, aiming at this terribly ambitious set of goals is substantively mistaken. There seem to be two considerations that Sen is relying on in support of this second claim just above. On the one hand, he thinks that social justice is intrinsically pluralistic in character, so it will often make inconsistent demands. He claims that there are “genuinely plural, and sometimes conflicting, general concerns that bear on our understanding of justice.” (See Sen, The Idea of Justice, 2009, p. 57). And the fact that there is a sort of deep pluralism in the demands of justice is the lesson naturally drawn from Sen’s parable of the flute and the three children (see Sen, The Idea of Justice, 2009, pp. 12-13 and p. 106). If that is correct, there simply will be no coherently unified story to tell about those demands, even where, as in the social contract model, everyone’s impartial reasons are being fully expressed and fairly consulted. One might presume against this that there is some unified answer to the question of what social justice requires in and perhaps between contemporary societies, albeit perhaps expressible only as a very abstract set of norms, in some order of priority. This is the assumption of most philosophers who inquire into the nature of social justice. There are two issues worth considering just here. First, Sen does not give a decisive argument for the controversial view that justice is intrinsically pluralistic even at a quite general level, and the jury appears to be out, maybe permanently so, on that question. Second, if he were right about this, that should not be particularly comforting for the reform-minded theorist of justice of the proposed new comparative style. For in that eventuality, things would be even murkier than on the competing monistic picture. We would be in the unenviable position of weighing multiple competing demands of the various justices along with all the familiar other possibly competing demands imposed on us by such alleged social virtues as: security against invasion, the very efficient provision of basic material goods, high rates of growth in GDP, high average living standard, or, in a more philosophical gear, maximal well-being. To put it simply, if social justice itself genuinely pulls us in multiple and even opposed directions, there may be no grounds for making even rough comparisons of relative justice and injustice as such. Pointing out that we can and do make choices in circumstances wherein we weigh goods that cannot themselves be made fully commensurate is not a good defence here (see Sen, The Idea of Justice, 2009, p. 241). In short, if Sen leans too heavily on the alleged fact of robust pluralism, then he undermines the grounds for thinking that there could be a comparative theory of justice at all. 214 Indian Journal of Human Development Sen’s other reason for thinking that the complete description of societal justice (and its realization) is an inapt aim has to do with the thought that it would be such a difficult task to complete. This is quite clear in the following: How complete should the assessment be? In the “totalist” approach that characterizes the standard theories of justice, including Rawls' incompleteness tends to appear as a failure…Indeed, the survival of incompleteness is sometimes seen as a defect of a theory of justice, which calls into question the positive assertion such a theory makes. In fact, a theory of justice that makes systematic room for incompleteness can allow one to arrive at quite strong… judgments, without having to find highly differentiated assessments of every political and social arrangement in comparison with every other such arrangement (for example addressing such questions as: exactly how much tax should be put on the sale of petrol in any particular country, for environmental reasons?) (Sen, The Idea of Justice, 2009, p. 103, emphasis added). Sen seems to be thinking that a complete theory of justice is one that will address every practical scenario generating a need for collective or cooperative decision that might come up in the human circumstances of justice. Such a theory would not only descry a coherent system of social institutions but would provide a detailed conceptual structure suitable for determining what justice calls for, in actions, institutions, and policies given whatever circumstances we find ourselves in, and with whatever preferences we might have. It seems that the theory would contain both a highly detailed model of the just society, and also reliable procedures for getting there and for maintaining justice once it is achieved. Sen suggests that this sort of (hopelessly) extreme comprehensiveness is precisely what the transcendental approach, as he calls it, aims at, that is, it aims at “a complete resolution of all the existing decisional issues about societal organization.” (See Sen, “What Do We Want from a Theory of Justice?”, 2006, p. 236.) This is a grand aim indeed. I am inclined to accept, with Sen, that this aim is indeed far too grand to be seriously pursued, and that it reflects confusion. But is one stuck with this aim merely in pursuing the question in view in the relevant fashion? That does not seem to be the case. Let us now consider Rawls' work in this connection, for it is Sen’s paradigm case. Rawls' dominant focus was indeed the topic of social justice in modern mass democracies and Sen is on solid ground to count him as pursuing a version of the grand question by appealing to a development of the idea of the social contract. Yet, in several places, Rawls also explicitly denies that he has the aim of settling in advance, by means of his theory, every practical question that might possibly arise in the circumstances of justice, even for those imperfect contemporary democracies that his theory speaks to most directly. He simply is not aiming at that sort of absolute theoretical comprehensiveness. Consider the following late discussion of the political conception of justice and the conception of the basic structure. The role of a political conception of justice however is not to say exactly how these questions are to be settled, but to set out a framework of thought within which they can be approached. Were we to lay down a definition of the basic structure Against Sen Against Rawls on Justice 215 that draws sharp boundaries, not only would we go beyond what that rough idea could reasonably contain, but we would risk wrongly prejudging what more specific or future conditions may call for, thus making justice as fairness unable to adjust to different circumstances. For our judgments to be reasonable, they must usually be informed by an awareness of those more specific circumstances (See Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, 2001b, p. 12). Rawls, as we can see, is indeed pursuing the grand question, while self-consciously explicitly abjuring the ambitious theoretical aim. Sen, however, takes this aim to follow from that pursuit. It follows that if Rawls is correct about the nature of his own theory, and if his project is roughly coherent (as it seems), Sen is wrong. It is possible to pursue the grand question without aiming at absolute theoretical comprehensiveness. Perhaps it will be thought that since the above passage appears relatively late in Rawls's career, it may not reflect the truth about the view in its dominant form. Perhaps, as Sen puts it, Rawls has telling “second thoughts” on this score, the implications of which are not fully worked out (see Sen, The Idea of Justice, 2009, p. 58). I am not convinced. It seems clear from the canonical expression of the view in A Theory of Justice that Rawls never embraced the sort of theoretical comprehensiveness that Sen attributes to him.5 Moreover, I think that there is general reason to doubt that pursuing the grand question requires one to embrace the aim of total (practical-) theoretical comprehensiveness. Suppose that some philosopher embraces a substantial theoretical modesty when it comes to ethics and political philosophy, or, in general, the demands of practical reason. We might imagine that she has become convinced that practical wisdom is uncodifiable, and accordingly also convinced that the relevant idea of a complete theory of perfect social justice is a misleading chimera.6 Do we insist that this philosopher somehow contradicts herself if she nonetheless vigorously pursues the grand question in a contractual vein? Is there something self-defeating about combining moral-theoretical modesty with the pursuit of the grand question of justice in the style of Rawls? I see no reason to think so. Such a philosopher perhaps will insist on the importance of attending to details if we are to uncover anything useful for action. She would remind us that the general principles of justice are always subject to revision and often require supplementation, or filling in, in order to express the relevant provisional practical truth, or that reflective equilibrium is always somewhat provisional. But being committed to this sort of theoretical modesty is not in any tension with the vigorous pursuit of the grand question. Despite these considerations, Sen could yet conceivably nonetheless be correct and Rawls incorrect about the Rawlsian view, and more generally about the social contract approach. But if that were so, we would not expect to find principles useful for making comparisons of relative justice nested within, and derivable from, the theories that this approach yields. Yet we do find such principles. And worse still, for Sen’s line of objection, we find principles that manifestly call upon us to make comparisons. Consider Rawls' difference principle, which roughly holds that social and economic inequalities are to be arranged to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged members 216 Indian Journal of Human Development of society (see Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 1971, p. 302). The basic implication is that any society S will count as just only when the social and economic inequalities are such that the position of those worst off relative to the other members of S, are better off in absolute terms than are the worst off members of every feasible alternative: S*, S**, etc. This is not a sufficient condition of social justice, according to Rawls, but it is in his view a necessary one. Now, not only can we not apply the difference principle in assessment of the justice of some society S except by making comparisons with other possible or actual societies, we cannot really understand the difference principle except as calling for comparative judgments. This is so since Rawls views the principle as a guiding choice between feasible alternatives, one of which may be actual. Manifestly then, one can pursue the grand question, and in so doing, develop the conceptual materials for making comparative judgments of justice. Sen grudgingly admits as much at one point in The Idea of Justice (see Sen, The Idea of Justice, 2009, p. 97). Consider next the thought that some explicitly comparative approach abjuring the grand question is thereby to be preferred to the transcendental approach. Sen supports this by arguing that achieving the aim of the transcendental approach is neither sufficient nor necessary for producing the relevant comparisons (see Sen, The Idea of Justice, 2009, pp. 98-102.) Let us consider this. As a matter of logic, it is true that possessing even some ideally complete theory of the just society does not, by itself, rank any given set of societies in point of justice. Even achieving the aim of the transcendental approach, as Sen describes it, were that possible, would not automatically generate comparisons. But this is equally true of accounts of justice explicitly focused on comparison and which are designed to accommodate incompleteness! It is of course only when it is conjoined with some relevant information about those societies—their historical and cultural circumstances, and so on—that any theory can provide the cognitive materials needed to make the relevant judgments. Once conjoined with relevant information, a theory generated by either approach may be quite useful for making comparisons. For illustration, consider again Rawls's justice as fairness with its two principles of justice, in lexical order.7 Recall that the first principle calls for the equal protection of the basic liberties, and that the second demands both protection for equitable opportunity to compete for attractive positions, and that any remaining inequalities serve the advantage of the least well-off members of society, relative to feasible alternatives. Suppose that the conditions on the ground are as follows. Three societies—S, S*, and S**— are each apparently feasible alternatives of the others. In society S, there are barriers to advancement and political participation, entrenched in positive law, directed against the members of a particular ethnic group on the sole grounds of membership in that group. Further, the economic institutions of S are rife with corruption and inefficiency, and shot through with extremes of income and wealth inequality kept in place by pervasive racism. Here, it seems as if neither of Rawls's principles is met. In society S*, let us suppose that the first principle is met, since there is a familiar set of enshrined constitutional protections of a version of the equal basic liberties that are reasonably effectively enforced. But, let us also suppose that the worst off in S* Against Sen Against Rawls on Justice 217 are plainly not as well off as are the worst off in society S**, though better off than S.8 On still further supposition, in S**, both principles are arguably met, for, as in S*, the constitutional protections are in place and enforced. Let us also assume that these are realistic cases in that none of these societies is perfectly well-ordered under any theory of justice. When made aware of these empirical conditions, the Rawlsian theorist is surely in a cognitive position to rank the three societies in point of justice. If she has had her morning coffee, she would rank S** as just, S* as partly just, and S as unjust. Notice that in the absence of her grasp of Rawls's specific theory, she might well be unable to rank S* and S** differentially, in point of justice, that is, her grasp of the theory allows her to judge that S** is more just insofar as the inequalities are organized to the benefit of the least advantaged. The grasp of the theory is perhaps usefully thought of as an INUS condition for making the comparative judgments. That is, perhaps it is an individually insufficient but non-redundant part of a set of conditions that are jointly unnecessary but here and now sufficient to produce the comparative judgments (see J.L. Mackie, The Cement of the Universe, 1980). In any event, it is clear that Sen’s original claim that no “transcendental theory of justice” even if “entirely successful in answering that classic question…would …yield—directly or indirectly—a comparative framework… needed for the actual assessment of justice” is false (see Sen, “What Do We Want from a Theory of Justice?”, 2006, p. 236). But perhaps the reader is unimpressed with my hypothetical and terribly abstract example of the Rawlsian apparatus in action. Suppose one thinks that, in practice, social contract philosophy, both generally, and in its specifically Rawlsian version, is likely to lead one down unproductive paths from the point of view of realizing justice. Against this empirical claim, consider the work of Thomas Pogge, a doctoral student of Rawls and an eminent political philosopher in his own right (see Pogge, World Poverty and Human Rights, 2008). Pogge has been working towards realizing a Rawlsian conception of justice for many years. He is particularly interested in issues of global justice, and is sympathetic in places to the idea of a global analogue of the Rawlsian hypothetical Original Position (OP), one that takes individuals—and not peoples—to be the represented parties (see, for example, Pogge, “An Egalitarian Law of Peoples”, 1994, pp. 195-224). Very simply, Pogge takes it that the reasoning exhibited by the representatives in the global OP would license at the very least the justice of a global tax on the extraction of non-renewable resources, with the proceeds intended to benefit the globally worst-off. More recently, he has been working on institutionally realizing the idea of a Health Impact Fund to reduce the burden of preventive disease on the world’s poor, and in general, on issues of global poverty relief. It seems to be obvious that in Pogge’s case, his Rawlsianism has productively and directly informed his work, justifying controversial claims about justice, though it has, of course, not been solely determinative. Sen is, of course, familiar with Pogge’s work, but it gets extremely short shrift in The Idea of Justice. Sen’s critical comment on Pogge that “the idea of one global exercise of social contract for the entire world population would appear to be deeply unrealistic” does not bear much scrutiny.9 218 Indian Journal of Human Development It is obviously true that one need not have a precisely and elaborately detailed complete theory of justice (in the relevant sense) in order to have some basis for making comparative judgments. We should accept Sen’s view that this sort of theory is not a necessary condition for comparison (and so for achieving reasoned reform) here and now. But what does one need and how should one proceed? If one is interested in thinking systematically about the basic demands of justice and then comparing some set of societies’ relative distances from meeting those demands, it remains clear, Sen’s arguments to the contrary notwithstanding, that a good way to begin is with the pursuit of the grand question. Sen is undoubtedly correct in thinking that it is possible to give reasons for a choice, and even to secure some agreement, without presupposing total unanimity of well-ordered preferences, or complete knowledge within a community of choice. But part of the strength of the Rawlsian perspective, and of that afforded to us by the social contract mode generally, is to get some significant traction on the question of social justice that rises above empirically given preferences. These are devices for modelling reflectively sound reasoning. It seems to me that there is no good reason for thinking that the partial social ordering generated by a congruence of, say, a majority of a given group’s set of preference orderings is per se to be given special weight when thinking about what justice requires. In the discussion in the concluding pages of his book, Sen gestures towards considerations of public reasons and impartiality as necessary filters for arriving at a sensible inference (see Sen, The Idea of Justice, 2009, pp. 398-99). Yet this seems to push us towards a Rawlsian model. Allow me to briefly consider some of the remaining charges levelled in the book. First, consider what I call procedural parochialism. In a move partly inspired by his love for Smith’s social thought, Sen argues that an impartial outside observer may be in a better position to sort out what justice requires in some concrete social setting than is a person whose life and livelihood are bound up in that locale. Thus, if an actual group were to embark on an attempt to engage in public reason about the rules of the game for themselves, the views of an outsider might be useful for blocking local prejudice or personal and potentially divisive interest from playing the wrong sort of role (see Sen, The Idea of Justice, 2009, p. 70). This might be correct in any particular case, though it seems like an entirely contingent matter. But it does not amount to a sound criticism of Rawls or of all contractualist ways of framing the relevant issues. After all, the very point of the Rawlsian model, with its ideally well-informed but crucially ignorant hypothetical representatives, is to emphasize the importance of impartiality. Rawls and related thinkers are also charged with being wrongly narrowly focused on institutions as the site of social justice. The thought here is that if we focus narrowly on our favoured institutions as manifestations of justice—for example, properly regulated relatively transparent markets, formal democratic electoral procedures, formal equality before the law— once these institutions are somehow concretely realized in the world, we may fail to take account of the effects that these may be having on actual person’s lives. As I noted above, Sen is to be commended for emphasizing, as fundamental, the realization of valued forms of functioning. But, again, this is not a particularly Against Sen Against Rawls on Justice 219 devastating criticism of Rawls. The latter attends to the basic structure of society as that over which the principles are properly authoritative precisely because in human social life, the nature of the overall institutional structure has thoroughgoing effects on the lives of actual people. It is for this reason that Rawls favours maximin as a theory of principle choice, rather than some other more familiar and less risk-averse strategy of choice under uncertainty.10 So it seems perverse to charge Rawls with neglecting this.11 The alleged populational plasticity problem is the final one that I will consider. A relevant point is made particularly clearly in Derek Parfit’s magisterial Reasons and Persons, viz., that choices of social policy in some society will affect the character and size of the future population of that same society (see Parfit, Reasons and Persons, 1984, pp. 355-77). Parfit was worried over the moral implications of this, which he calls the Non-Identity Problem. Sen thinks that a version of this problem arises in an acute form for Rawls and renders his account of justice incoherent. The thought is that the number of participants in the hypothetical assembly is indeterminate as it is affected by the decisions of that very assembly. Since the choice of principles will affect the basic structure and the character of the basic structure will affect the size and character of the population, the model is presumed to be unworkable (see Sen, The Idea of Justice, 2009, p. 145). It is admittedly difficult to know how to precisely take the interests of potential future people into account when thinking about the requirements of justice. After all, it is difficult to see how decisions we take now could be said either to help or to harm people who do not exist and whose very existence is causally down- stream from those decisions! But surely it is coherent to ask, of the members of a given presently living generation of citizens, how they could be represented to reason in a version of the Rawlsian OP. We are simply not required to assume that every possible future person be given a voice in the hypothetical procedure. In conclusion, Sen is certainly correct to think that comparisons of relative justice and injustice should concern those who care about actually making the world a better place. He is also on strong ground in insisting that aiming at a certain kind of theoretical perfection is quixotic and unnecessary for making useful comparative judgments. But these are not things that Rawls, the Rawslians, or social contract thinkers would generally deny. Nor does any feature of their general way of proceeding make them incapable of appreciating these points. There is one final point to register. I would like to resist cynicism about the prospects of concretely engaged political philosophy. Yet it appears highly unlikely that the genuine practical problems posed by the existence of serious injustices, and their going unaddressed, will be resolved by some general paradigm shift—perhaps moving away from the social contract model—in our theories of justice. What mainly keeps us from doing more to reduce injustice is not I think an over-utopian or obsessively perfectionist streak in our theories of justice. Instead, it is the drearily familiar litany of factors: ignorance, selfishness, confusion about what is, on reflection, important in life, failures of will, the distractions of living in a consumer society, the struggles of keeping life and limb together, the ideological state apparatuses, the dominance of our political institutions by the corrupt, the self-interested, and the incompetent, and 220 Indian Journal of Human Development so on. In pursuing the grand question publicly, we open up the reflective space to articulate and then to begin to redress these factors. That openness and the subsequent articulation of the demands of justice remains part of what we ought to want from the activity of theorizing about justice. NOTES 1. For a crisp recent statement of Sen’s sense of his own intellectual and personal relation to Rawls, see his “The Place of Capability in a Theory of Justice” 2010, pp. 239-253. 2. See John Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 1971. I assume that readers are familiar with Rawls' account of justice. In short, he seeks to model relevant impartiality in the reasoned choice of principles of social justice (viewed as governing the institutionally realized distribution of benefits and burdens attendant upon any society) by blocking the hypothetical procedure of choice from reliance on reasons which he thinks are arbitrary from the moral point of view. One’s representative cannot, for example, bargain in a self-interested way from one’s place in the social hierarchy to a set of principles, differentially favouring those in that place, since that sort of reasoning is blocked by what he calls the ‘veil of ignorance’. 3. It is not clear that this insight is the source of a powerful objection to Rawls. See Footnote 3 in John Rawls, The Law of Peoples, 2001 [1999], p. 13. 4. See in particular Amartya Sen, “What Do We Want from a Theory of Justice?”, 2006, pp. 215-38. See also Sen, “The Place of Capability in a Theory of Justice”, 2010, and his introduction in Adam Smith, The Theory of Moral Sentiments, 2009 [1790], pp. vi-xxvi. 5. See, for example, Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 1971, p. 566. “Now this sequence does not aim at the complete specification of conduct. Rather the idea is to approximate the boundaries, however vague, within which individuals and associations are at liberty to advance their aims and deliberative rationality has free play.” 6. The uncodifiability thesis holds that the deliverances of practical reason (whether judgments or actions) are, in general, not to be understood as consisting in the applications of a rule, every instance of which can be completely specified in advance. It is linked with what is sometimes called anti-theory in moral philosophy. For discussion of and motivation for the uncodifiability thesis, see John McDowell, “Virtue and Reason”, 1998 [1979]. 7. See Rawls, Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, 2001b, pp. 42-43. The idea that the principles would be chosen in lexical order reflects the concern that roughly we should not simply trade off economic gains at the expense of sacrificing the basic liberties. 8. I am not assuming that ‘better off than’ always names a relation strictly transitive at the level of general logic. See Stuart Rachels, “Counter-examples to the Transitivity of Better Than”, 1998, pp. 71-83. But I am assuming that here those worst off in S are both more worse off than the relevant those in S* and way more worse off than the relevant those in S**! 9. See Sen, The Idea of Justice, 2009, pp. 140-41. Rawls' original model and its global analogues are, of course, hypothetical, and it simply isn’t clear what sort of “exercise” Sen is labelling as “unrealistic”. If there is a sensible objection here, Sen has not succeeded in making it. Presumably, he is intending to side with Thomas Nagel in emphasizing the idea that at present, the political institutions that would allow for an immediate implementation of ambitious global social policies related to justice are simply not developed enough. Yet, it is not remotely clear that this constitutes a reason counting against the relevance, to global justice, of the Rawlsian apparatus. See Thomas Nagel, “The Problem of Global Justice”, 2005, pp. 113-47. 10. To put it simply, the maximin principle tells one to maximize the minimum or to choose the scenario with the best of the worst achievable outcomes across a range of feasible scenarios. It expresses a high degree of risk aversion. See Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 1971, pp. 152-53. 11. Compare Sen, The Idea of Justice, 2009, p. 85 and Rawls, The Law of Peoples, 2001a, Footnote 3, p. 13. Against Sen Against Rawls on Justice 221 REFERENCES Mackie, J.L. (1980). The Cement of the Universe, Oxford University Press, Oxford. McDowell, John (1998) [1979]. “Virtue and Reason”, Mind Value and Reality, Harvard University Press, New York. Nagel, Thomas (2005). “The Problem of Global Justice”, Philosophy and Public Affairs, Vol. 33, No. 2, pp. 113-47. Parfit, Derek (1984). Reasons and Persons, Clarendon Press, Oxford. Pogge, Thomas (1994). “An Egalitarian Law of Peoples”, Philosophy and Public Affairs, Vol. 23, No. 3, pp. 195-224. —— (2008). World Poverty and Human Rights, (Second edition), Polity Press, Cambridge. Rachels, Stuart (1998). “Counter-examples to the Transitivity of Better Than”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 76, No. 1, March, pp. 71-83. Rawls, John (1971). A Theory of Justice, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA. —— (2001a) [1999]. The Law of Peoples, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA. —— (2001b). Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, Edited by Erin Kelly, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA. Sen, Amartya (1980). “Equality of What?”, in S. McMurrin, Tanner Lectures on Human Values, Vol. I, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. —— (2006). “What Do We Want from a Theory of Justice?”, The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. CIII, No. 5, May, pp. 215-38. —— (2009). The Idea of Justice, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA. —— (2009) [1790]. “Introduction” in Adam Smith, The Theory of Moral Sentiments, Penguin Books, New York, 2009 pp. vi-xxvi. —— (2010). “The Place of Capability in a Theory of Justice”, in Harry Brighouse and Ingrid Robeyns (eds) Measuring Justice, Cambridge University Press, New York, pp. 239-53. 222 Indian Journal of Human Development front 13-Evan Riley back work_enmjhmtgpvb6dbeechvgoqwj3i ---- Page Not Found | Rutgers Law Skip to main content Apply Cost Visit Universitywide New Brunswick RBHS Newark Camden Online Rutgers Health Select resource to search THIS SITE This site All sites People Events Buildings RBHS Search term Search submit Menu Rutgers Law Main menu Why Law? Why Law? One Rutgers Law Our Locations Leadership Statement on Black Lives Matter Message from the Co-Deans Alumni Network The Brief Academics Academics Degree Offerings Curriculum Master Course Lists Academic Affairs Student Life Law Library Continuing Education Undergraduate Legal Studies Admissions ABA Standard 509 Disclosure Admissions Admitted Students Apply Cost Fall 2020 FAQ International Students Minority Student Program Non-Discrimination Policy Part-Time/Transfer/Visiting Students Quick Facts Recruiting Events Social Justice Scholars Students with Disabilities Visiting & Virtual Events Faculty Faculty Faculty Directory Staff Directory Library Directory Administration Directory Faculty by Expertise Academic Centers Faculty Insights Blog Real-World Experience Real-World Experience Legal Writing Field Placements International Programs Judicial Externships Law Journals Legal Clinics Mock Trial Participation Pro Bono & Public Interest Rutgers Law Associates Fellowship Program Career Development CAREER DEVELOPMENT About the Center for Career Development Student Information Alumni Information Employer Information Career Pathways Contact Career Development Center ALUMNI Alumni Get Involved Alumni Events Alumni Updates Giving Alumni Resources Rutgers School of Law – Camden Alumni Association Rutgers Law School – Newark Alumni Association Info Info Commencement Current Students Faculty & Staff Alumni Donors & Friends Legal Assistance Legal Community Prospective Students Rutgers.edu Links Universitywide New Brunswick RBHS Newark Camden Online Rutgers Health Page Not Found The page you are looking for has moved. Here are pages you might find helpful: Admissions Current Student Log-in Faculty and Staff Log-in Academics Questions about the new site can be shared with Elizabeth Moore in Newark. Request Info Apply Directions Visit Law Clinics Legal Assistance Events News NEWS ARCHIVE Donate Footer Right CAMDEN Rutgers Law School 217 North Fifth Street Camden, NJ 08102 Phone: (856) 225-6375 NEWARK Rutgers Law School 123 Washington Street Newark, NJ 07102 Phone: (973) 353-5561 ABA Required Disclosures             COPYRIGHT ©2016, RUTGERS, THE STATE UNIVERSITY OF NEW JERSEY, AN EQUAL OPPORTUNITY, AFFIRMATIVE ACTION INSTITUTION. ALL RIGHTS RESERVED. work_eo2zbuypsvchbbbbob5yy5dhdi ---- TEACHING SOCIAL JUSTICE ADVOCACY: USING THE METAPHOR OF A QUILT Psychology of Women Quarterly, 34 (2010), 550–557. Wiley Periodicals, Inc. Printed in the USA. Copyright C© 2010 Division 35, American Psychological Association. 0361-6843/10 TEACHING BRIEFS TEACHING SOCIAL JUSTICE ADVOCACY: USING THE METAPHOR OF A QUILT Recent literature has called for the counseling and psycho- logical field to integrate social justice issues into student training (Goodman et al., 2004; Prilleltensky, 1997; Singh et al., 2010). However, there has been little attention to the pedagogy of social justice advocacy and how instructors may bring social justice issues to life for students. Fortu- nately, feminist pedagogy has provided a rich foundation of the relational skills instructors may infuse in their teaching (Kimmel & Worell, 1997). These feminist pedagogical strategies have explored how instructors may address is- sues of power and authority in the classroom through self-reflection and the development of student-teacher col- laborative relationships in the construction of knowledge. Feminist pedagogy has also moved beyond a focus on in- structor pedagogical skills, seeking to understand the influ- ence of these skills on students’ experiences in the class- room (Stake & Hoffman, 2000). The purpose of my essay is to discuss how the metaphor of a “social justice quilt” is used as a feminist pedagogical tool to encourage a collaborative student-teacher exploration of the personal experiences of advocacy in a doctoral-level class on social justice issues. Teaching About Privilege and Oppression One of the challenges of teaching about social justice is- sues in counseling and psychology is the construction of a teaching environment where students can empower them- selves to explore their personal experiences of privilege and oppression. Multicultural counseling and psychology courses highlight the importance of students’ understand- ing of the cultural worldviews of themselves and others (Sue & Sue, 2008). However, social justice courses de- mand that students move beyond a multicultural under- standing of diverse cultural worldviews so that they them- selves may become social change agents and take action on issues of equity and justice (Goodman et al., 2004). Therefore, students must have a thorough understanding of not only strategies for social justice, but also—and perhaps more importantly—the ways they have specifically bene- fitted from previous advocacy movements. In this regard, Address correspondence and reprint requests to: Anneliese A. Singh, Department of Counseling & Human Development Ser- vices, The University of Georgia, 402 Aderhold Hall, Athens, GA 30602-7142. E-mail: asingh@uga.edu students have the opportunity to see and experience social justice issues in a more personal manner—rather than as a construct that is more abstract than relevant and meaning- ful in their lives. The Quilt as a Metaphor for Social Justice Advocacy I am fortunate because the doctoral program in which I work is grounded in social justice principles; these prin- ciples influence students’ learning and values before they enroll in the social justice course with me. Social justice is both the mission and aim of our program. However, in previous experiences of teaching about social justice issues at both the masters and doctoral-level outside this program, I had experiences with students that may be far too com- mon for instructors who teach with these commitments. For instance, although some students could talk about the importance of social justice, they often struggled to connect the concept of the “personal is political” with individual psy- chotherapy and clients’ experiences of oppression outside the therapist’s office. Other students saw social justice as a construct that revealed a “liberal bias” in counseling and psychology that had no place in the teaching of counseling and psychology. Still others experienced intense passion around the subject of social justice, yet they felt just as in- tensely overwhelmed by how psychotherapists could ever address the immense issues entailed in social justice advo- cacy. For these reasons, I shifted my pedagogy from assert- ing the importance of social justice and defining its mean- ing in the counseling and psychology literature. Instead, I returned to the feminist foundation of my own peda- gogy and endeavored to construct a new foundation from which I could collaboratively construct knowledge with stu- dents about the personal meaning and relevance social jus- tice advocacy has for both the instructor’s and students’ lives. Using the metaphor of a quilt, I developed an assign- ment that positioned the “personal is political” and called it the “Social Justice Quilt.” As I describe the assignment, I will take direct quotes from the syllabus for the doctoral- level social justice course. (The full syllabus is avaliable online.) Teaching in the South, the metaphor of a quilt has spe- cific and personal meanings for some students. More often than not, students have a quilt that was made for them at their birth and/or have heard stories of quilts made by careful, meticulous hands within their family. Quilts 550 PWQ Teaching Briefs, December 2010 551 themselves have particular meaning in terms of gender and race/ethnicity. The hands that often make quilts belong to generations of creative, strong women in families. In terms of race/ethnicity—often one of the most challenging oppressions from which to explore and own one’s experi- ences of privilege and oppression—quilts also have partic- ular meaning. People of Black/African heritage who were enslaved in the United States often made quilts that en- sured the continuation of cultural symbols and values and that were also used as maps encoding pathways to libera- tion. Therefore, I use the following quote from Milo (1995) to introduce the activity: The quilt is used symbolically for the feelings about race and ethnicity that cover us while we sleep, com- fort us against the cold, and are folded and neatly put away during various seasons of the year. They may be pieced together using one small scrap at a time, sometimes cut into beautiful designs from fancy ma- terials, at other times cut into odd shapes from plain, ordinary, well-worn fabric, and stitched by a machine instead of by hand. Regardless of any or all of these origins, they are bound with small stitches, bordered, have padded insulation, and are backed with substan- tial material. We think of them as so necessary to sur- vival that we give them to babies, and often pack them when going on lone and desolate journeys. Some are tattered and torn from overuse, others are carted out for display, company, or special occasions; but we each own one (p. 4). Using this quote to frame both the personal and political aspects of quilt making, students and I share stories about actual quilts in our lives. I describe the quilt that my White grandmother made for me on the occasion of my birth— replete with its femininity in the form of light pink cotton threads and large crocheted flowers—to invite the personal stories of quilts into the room. Reading Milo’s (1995) quote aloud with the class, we then connect the metaphor of warmth and comfort to the construct of privilege—the un- earned benefits that are handed down generationally and constructed by our foremothers and forefathers. Inevitably as a class, we then explore how social justice advocacy is both a strategy to “level the playing field” with regard to privilege and oppression experiences and the difficulty of identifying privilege because of its insidiousness, its invisi- bility, and its protected status through systems of privilege and oppression. After discussing the histories and her-stories of quilts and the challenge of identifying systems of privilege and the importance of social justice advocacy, we as a class discuss the importance of creativity in becoming a social change agent. Students are encouraged to use their own creative vision to bring their own social justice quilt to life. Their social justice quilts can draw from many forms of media. They may have an emphasis on using found artifacts and objects in their lives and have a goal to link social justice theories in the course to their own personal life experiences: For this project, use everyday objects (e.g., mag- azine cut-outs, photographs, found objects around your home or workplace) to create a “social justice quilt” that represents the most salient aspects of your identity (e.g., race/ethnicity, gender, sexual orienta- tion) and history of personal social justice advocacy that shape how you view social justice theory, the nature of human challenges and resilience, and the reasons you have chosen a helping profession. When students read this description of the activity from the syllabus, many questions arise. Notably, doctoral-level students endeavor to understand the boundaries of the as- signment and the specific level of personal disclosure ex- pected from them in the presentation of their quilts. Prior to discussing these expectations further, we begin a discus- sion of the awareness they may or may not have of social justice movements in order to illustrate the purpose of the social justice advocacy. Connecting to Social Justice Movements The core component of the social justice quilt assignment is the connection between the instructor’s and students’ expe- riences of privilege and oppression with larger social justice movements. Students inevitably have numerous questions about the definition of what a social justice movement is. I initially invite students to brainstorm as a group to de- fine social justice, and students typically share words that I write on the board—such as “liberation,” “rights,” and “eq- uity.” A discussion invariably follows where students ask what actions “count” in terms of social justice actions for psychologists. I share recent definitions of social justice by scholars in psychology, such as Goodman et al. (2004, p. 793), as an exemplar: “Scholarship and professional ac- tion designed to change societal values, structures, poli- cies and practices, such that disadvantaged or marginal- ized groups gain increased access to these tools of self- determination.” Then, I invite students to share what comes to mind for them when they hear the words “social justice.” Students often identify the civil rights movement of the 1960s, the peace movement of the 1970s, and the women’s liberation movement as examples of social justice advocacy. I sketch out a timeline for the movements they name, and then I make a note of the large amount of white space (repre- senting gaps in time) that has not been filled with other social justice movements. Students have rich discussions of why this knowledge may have been missing from their history textbooks and/or from discussions within their fam- ily. Often, as the discussion continues, students begin to identify additional social justice movements in the United States, such as labor rights. Students then begin to ques- tion the U.S.-centricity of their knowledge base and identify 552 PWQ TEACHING BRIEFS, DECEMBER 2010 international social justice movements—typically related to women’s rights and violence. When students understand the parameters of the assign- ment, I then present my own social justice quilt. Exploring the specific intersections of privilege and oppression in my life, I use a Powerpoint presentation with artifacts from my home (e.g., photos, drawings) to bring my social justice quilt to life. I discuss the varying degrees of class privilege I have had over the lifespan, from working class to poverty to upper middle class to middle class. As a queer South Asian woman born in New Orleans, I discuss how my fa- ther’s academic class bought me the value of education and eventually brought our family to various class levels and out of poverty. I also discuss the ways that my class status intersected with my race/ethnicity, gender, geographic re- gion, and sexual orientation. As I explore these identities and intersections, I endeavor to link the ways I specifically benefitted from previous social justice movements, such as the civil rights movement, women’s liberation movement, Indian liberation movement from British colonialism, and labor rights movements in both the United States and In- dia. I welcome personal questions from students at the end of the presentation, and then I take further questions about the assignment. For the students’ presentations of their Social Justice Quilts, I intentionally schedule the presentations at the beginning of each class in order to ensure that we as a class infuse feminist philosophies of the “personal is polit- ical” into each class. I then have the ability to weave the personal examples of benefiting from social justice move- ments from students’ own lives into the more general class discussions. For instance, if we are discussing theories of counseling and psychology, I integrate a class exploration of how issues of privilege and oppression they identified in the Social Justice Quilts are connected to the topic. I invite each student in these discussions to identify personal biases and assumptions they hold (or have held in the past) about social justice issues (e.g., immigration reform, reproductive justice). Overall, the students’ presentations have been creative, forward thinking, inspiring, and emotional. For instance, a White heterosexual student in her late 20s who is a mother explored the complex intersections in her life of both priv- ilege (White, married to a man, Christian) with her expe- riences of being a woman and a mother. In terms of an identity that is typically marginalized, her gender, this stu- dent explored specific ways she was not connected to the women’s liberation movement and did not have information about this movement throughout her high school and col- lege experiences. This student discussed the isolation she has felt as a woman and mother, and how various privileged identities might have brought her access to resources, but did not mitigate the feelings of being “othered.” She also shared a renewed interest in reading about the women’s liberation movement and specifically becoming involved in third wave feminist movements. From Social Justice Learning to Action As hooks (2003) reminds us, feminist pedagogy at its best inspires not only social justice awareness, but also social justice change. One of the most rewarding aspects of the students’ sharing of their Social Justice Quilts has been witnessing how they integrate their own personal learning about advocacy into the ways they interact professionally with clients and personally with their kinship and peer net- works. For instance, one student (White woman) who works in school settings shared the following reflection about her transition from awareness to action in compiling her Social Justice Quilt project: I used to think, “Why is there a Black History month? There isn’t a White History month.” Now I see that everyday, every month is White History something. I would have also described myself as open-minded and accepting of others, but now that my perspec- tive has changed, I realize that I was accepting of others as to what I was comfortable accepting or I was open-minded about what topics I was comfort- able being open-minded about. Now, I make sure to speak up in school meetings about White priv- ilege. I talk to my family and friends about what I have learned. It’s hard for them to understand, but I can’t keep silent anymore. Now, I include issues of privilege and oppression in my case in- takes and write-ups. I track how oppressive experi- ences influence my clients’ achievement, hopes, and dreams. Interestingly, the Social Justice Quilt assignment also helps students who have typically seen themselves as hav- ing little privilege in their lives to see how they may have not considered privileged statuses they do have. Recog- nizing this privilege, these students often feel empowered by their Social Justice Quilts to use these statuses to in- teract differently with their clients even when identifying these privileged identities may be challenging. One student (African American man) shared: This assignment has been challenging. It was difficult to talk about some of my past experiences of privilege in being heterosexual because they are still so painful, especially when I bullied others because they were gay. However, I felt I needed to be completely honest in describing these experiences not only because they have created the impetus for my advocacy, but also because they have limited me in some ways from being as strong of an advocate as I would like to be. Now, people at work joke that I won’t stop talking about being a LGBTQ-ally. They can joke all they want. I won’t go back to being ignorant or not helping the LGBTQ kids. It would be criminal. PWQ Teaching Briefs, December 2010 553 Implications for Feminist and Social Justice Pedagogy There are several implications of the Social Justice Quilt for feminist and social justice pedagogy. As the field of counsel- ing and psychology recommits itself to values of social jus- tice, the inclusion of feminist practice, theory, research, and advocacy often becomes invisible to these discussions. The Social Justice Quilt breathes life into feminist pedagogy, constructing a space where students can inspire themselves to learn about the importance of feminist movements and their relationship to social justice values. Because many of the students in the class may not have previously learned about issues of social justice and their relationship to coun- seling and psychology, these discussions have the potential to become overwhelming to students. Therefore, instruc- tors using this activity should take an initial pulse of stu- dents’ knowledge of these issues at the beginning of class to assess the range of social justice awareness and knowl- edge. Then, instructors can ensure that students who are new to this topic and/or who have great passion for social justice advocacy may explore how to balance attention to social justice issues in the practice of counseling and psy- chology. Additionally, when instructors and students discuss so- cial justice issues in counseling and psychology, these dis- cussions often focus on the future action and social change that counselors and psychologists may engage in as helping professionals. This focus on students’ future roles as social change agents is indeed important; however, it can be chal- lenging for student trainees to understand the real impor- tance and meaning that social justice movements have for everyday people, human rights, and policy changes with- out understanding past history and her-story. The Social Justice Quilt supports a balance between two forces. One force looks back, so that students can “see” themselves in the history and her-story of liberation. The second force looks forward, so that they can see how they hold the prod- ucts of liberation (e.g., opportunities, resources, access) in addition to holding the power to create change on behalf of others. Finally, the Social Justice Quilt combines the best features of feminist pedagogy, such as attention to reflex- ivity, instructor power, and collaborative relationships with students in the construction of knowledge. In addition, it also provides an ongoing accountability check for the im- portance of making the “personal is political” in becoming a social change agent. REFERENCES Goodman, L. A., Liang, B., Helms, J. E., Latta, R. E., Sparks, E., & Weintraub, S. R. (2004). Training counseling psychol- ogists as social justice agents: Feminist and multicultural principles in action. The Counseling Psychologist, 32, 793– 837. Hooks, B. (2003). Teaching community: A pedagogy of hope. New York: Routledge. Kimmel, E., & Worell, J. (1997). Preaching what we practice: Principles and strategies of feminist pedagogy. In J. Worell & N. Johnson (Eds.), Shaping the future of feminist psy- chology: Education, research, and practice (pp. 148–154). Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. Prilleltensky, I. (1997). Values, assumptions, and practices: As- sessing the moral implications of psychological discourse and action. American Psychologist, 52, 517–535. Singh. A. A., Hofsess, C. D., Boyer, E. M., Kwong, A., Law, A. S. M., McLain, M., et al. (2010). Social justice and counseling psychology: Listening to the voices of doctoral trainees. The Counseling Psychologist, 38, 766–795. Stake, J. E., & Hoffman, F. L. (2000). Putting feminist pedagogy to the test: The experience of women’s studies from student and teacher perspectives. Psychology of Women Quarterly, 24, 30–38. Sue, D. W., & Sue, D. (2008). Counseling the culturally diverse: Theory and practice (5th ed.). New York: Wiley. SUPPORTING INFORMATION The following supporting information is available for this article online at http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/ journal/10.1111/(ISSN)1471-6402: Dr. Singh’s class syl- labus. Anneliese A. Singh, Ph.D., LPC, is an assistant professor in the department of Counseling and Human Development Services at The University of Georgia. Her research inter- ests include training and supervision on social justice issues in counseling and psychology. TEACHING CRITICAL THINKING ABOUT PSYCHOLOGY OF SEX AND GENDER In 1980, Professor Ronnie de Sousa, then head of the Uni- versity of Toronto Women’s Studies Programme, invited me to coordinate a course he had conceived, to be called “Scientific Perspectives on Sex and Gender.” I accepted on the condition that we teach it from a strong critical think- ing perspective. At that time, there was one full-year core course in Women’s Studies focused on history, philosophy, and literature and film. Dr. de Sousa’s plan was to focus a second full-year core course on the ways that researchers and theorists from the sciences—specifically, psychology, biology, and anthropology—investigated questions related to sex and gender. That year (and for some years thereafter), I coordinated that second course and gave the one-third of its lectures that were about psychology. Despite the important work of many second wave fem- inists, the vast majority of students who enrolled in the course had a great many beliefs about sex and gender dif- ferences in emotions, attitudes, cognition, and behavior Address correspondence and reprint requests to: Paula Ca- plan, 26 Alpine St. Cambridge, MA 02138. E-mail: paulacaplan@ gmail.com 554 PWQ TEACHING BRIEFS, DECEMBER 2010 for which there was little or no solid support from well designed, well executed, and responsibly interpreted research. Rather, their beliefs came partly from the mes- sages in popular media and partly from academic journals. I considered it important to have no prerequisites for the course. However, many students began with consid- erable anxiety about their ability to understand and think critically about scientific material. Thus, it was important to instill in them some confidence about approaching the topics in the course and applying a critical thinking ap- proach. Indeed, when I taught this material at Harvard University very recently, students who had been concen- trating in Psychology for two years or more reported that this was the first time they had been asked to think critically about psychological research. Some found it at first discon- certing to be asked to switch from the mental set that one student described as “the professor tells us what to read that is important and just learn it.” Despite some initial discomfort, however, most said that they ultimately found it liberating to be asked to think critically. Many said that the approach helped them understand the uneasiness they had experienced with some of the material that professors had assigned and discussed as though it represented facts, even though the studies sometimes were poorly conceived and designed and/or included unwarranted interpretations of data. Beginning with the first year that I taught the course at the University of Toronto, I found it frustrating that so little critique had been written about the psychological research about sex and gender. Ultimately, I co-wrote a book entitled Thinking Critically About Research on Sex and Gender, which was intended to fill this need (Caplan & Caplan, 1994). Two more recent editions of the book have subsequently been published (Caplan & Caplan, 1999, 2009). An important early step is to explain that there is noth- ing magical about critical thinking. This point has been true from the first time I co-taught “Scientific Perspectives on Sex and Gender” at the University of Toronto through my most recent teaching of it (as “Psychology of Sex and Gen- der” at Harvard University). As Jeremy B. Caplan and I have written (Caplan & Caplan, 2009), if one were walking along the sidewalk and saw a dog suddenly zoom straight up from the sidewalk into the air, certain questions would immediately come to mind (such as “What happened to gravity?”). Critical thinking about scientific theory and re- search is nothing more than logical, careful thinking, some of which requires no special training or information and some of which is easier once one knows some methods, principles, and conventions. It is also helpful for the student to understand that re- search about sex and gender is not free from subjectivity and bias. To convey this point, some historical perspective is useful. Students find it easier to spot the flaws in research from the 19th or early 20th centuries (Caplan & Caplan, 2009, Chapter 2) than in contemporary research. They can begin by reading about 19th-century researchers’ tireless efforts to discover some part of the brain where men’s su- perior intelligence resided and the way their theories and methodologies became protean as they repeatedly failed to make such a discovery. Often, they are amused by these long-ago researchers’ persistence and puzzled by the tenac- ity with which they clung to the claim of males’ superior intelligence and brains, despite evidence to the contrary. Thus, they have an interesting foundation for discussing contemporary efforts to discover a consistent sex differ- ence between the brains of girls and women and those of boys and men. This background makes it relatively easy to notice parallels between the two lines of research and the similarities of their flaws in theory, methodology, and interpretation of data (Caplan & Caplan, 2009, Chapter 3). It is important to say at the beginning of this course: “Virtually everyone believes certain things about sex and gender and sex differences to be true, but a major goal of our course is to find out what is accurate, based on the qual- ity of the research.” This is not like learning solid geometry or particle physics, because all our lives we are flooded with information about what we should and should not do and feel, depending greatly on whether we are classified as female or male. So, I say, “This course will resonate in an astonishing number of ways with your own life. Some will be positive, even liberating, but others may be deeply disconcerting. So, hold on to your hats.” I have sometimes had students tell me, even close to tears, that it is upset- ting to be asked to question so much of what they have always believed, especially because they often are not sure what to believe instead. For instance, they want to know, if men are not naturally aggressive and women naturally self-denying and patient, then what do we know about dif- ferences between them in these traits? Where will we find the certainty that can be somewhat comforting, even if lim- iting? My response begins with: “It is important to make decisions based on what is known, as well as on knowing what is not yet known. I would prefer to avoid making de- cisions based on unfounded claims about sex differences, no matter how widely they may be believed.” It is also im- portant to help students consider that their decisions about people’s behavior should be based on real understanding of research, rather than on irrelevant factors. Lest students believe that the instructor is simply a cur- mudgeon who refuses to say that some research is well done, it is important to say that some research is quite good. However, it is genuinely challenging to carry out re- search about human behavior. If this research is conducted in a laboratory, where many variables can be controlled, then it may be well done but help us little in understand- ing the real world. However, if it is carried out in the real world, then such a multitude of factors can influence the results that it is often difficult to know just what one can learn from such research. I explain that this does not mean that we should give up hope for carrying out high-quality research but only that we must understand the limitations PWQ Teaching Briefs, December 2010 555 of that endeavor and realize that perfect single studies are nonexistent. From the first meeting of this course, it is important to jump in immediately to talk about research questions, de- signs, and interpretations of results. One should not assume that using an extremely simple example will come across as silly or condescending. In fact, it is an effective way to ease them into a critical thinking approach and to provide an immediate experience in which they can recognize their ability to think critically. For instance, I tell them about the 7-year-old children with whom I first tried this approach (Caplan, Secord-Gilbert, & Staton, 1990; Caplan & Caplan, 2009). (Sometimes they are interested to learn that that took place with the third-grade class of my son, Jeremy Benjamin Caplan, who at 16 coauthored with me Thinking Critically About Research on Sex and Gender (Caplan & Caplan,1994) and who is now a cognitive neuroscientist at the University of Alberta.) After this description, I ask them to read and discuss Chapter 3 in Thinking Critically About Research on Sex and Gender, which my son wrote as an accessible way to introduce students to a great many of the most common methodological errors. In that chapter, he examines the question of whether there are sex differences in strength. Through that example, he describes numerous problems of methodology, ranging from choosing what to study, to designing the research, to carrying out the study, to inter- preting the results. That hypothetical example paves the way for discussion of actual studies and critiques of their methodology that we model in lectures with ample class participation. The class also reads chapters of the Caplan and Caplan (2009) book about particular topics, including research allegedly showing sex differences in certain emotions, certain kinds of behavior, cognitive performance, and the brain. It is helpful to introduce a simple document such as “How to Do a Critique” (see the Appendix) and to help students think through the steps involved in considering a study’s value. It is also helpful to introduce variety in the kinds of arti- cles you discuss and ask them to critique, including reports of research that appear in popular media and in schol- arly journal articles. Students can use the “How to Do a Critique” document and the chapter about methodologi- cal errors from the Caplan and Caplan (2009) book. For still more practice in discussion sections, students can be encouraged to bring in popular and scholarly articles for critical analysis. Early in the course, I have students work in small groups with the following instructions: Choose a topic related to sex and/or gender that in- terests you, and then within that topic area, choose a hypothesis or research question to investigate. To- gether, design the best study you can think of to test that hypothesis or address that question. Pro- duce a written description of your study, including the hypothesis or research question and the design of the study with regard to the participants, instru- ments or interventions, and procedures. Then, using the approach we have been employing in class, write a critique of your study. No piece of psychological research is ever perfect, and most are far from it, so do not be concerned when you notice that yours has flaws or limitations. [Depending on the course, I may ask the students to write their critiques individually or as a group.] Hand in the description of the study and the critique together. Time permitting, each small group can trade research designs with another group and critique each other’s design, a particularly good exercise for discussion sections. Also time permitting, students might design a simple enough study that they can actually carry out, such as observa- tions in a dining hall. Thus students acquire experience in identifying real-life limitations of executing even the best- conceived research. Then they write a critique that includes some of those limitations that they had not foreseen. When students design their own study, they understand some of the difficulties in trying to produce high-quality research about psychology of sex and gender. This project also re- lieves some of their uncertainty about whether they are qualified to understand and critique research. A next step is to choose an article from a popular medium and ask the students to write a three-page critique, again using the “How to Do a Critique” document as a guideline. I sometimes compare this exercise to workbooks’ “What’s Wrong With This Picture?” exercise, in which children are asked to identify all of the problems they can find. The instructor must provide very detailed feedback to the stu- dents so that they can see which steps from the critique document they have followed well and which steps require greater attention. Later in the course, I choose an article from a scholarly journal for the students to critique in the same way. During this time, in lectures and discussions, we use portions of many chapters in the Caplan and Caplan (2009) book. I often compare and contrast at least two articles of different quality about a given topic. This exercise gives students a sense of the problems in research about topics such as sex differences in mathematical abilities. They can also learn how the choice of research question, study design, and responsible interpretation of data can contribute to higher-quality work. One essential topic that is rarely addressed in writing about research on sex differences and similarities is that of intersex people, those who do not fit the usually strict def- initions of biological femaleness or of biological maleness (Fausto-Sterling, 2000). As Jeremy B. Caplan and I point out, the existence of people who are intersex has the potential to revolutionize the field of psycho- logical sex differences, because virtually every study 556 PWQ TEACHING BRIEFS, DECEMBER 2010 of psychological “sex differences” has been based on the erroneous assumption that only typical females and males were studied. Researchers in these stud- ies have virtually never done chromosomal analyses or physical examinations to determine a participant’s sex, and when classification by sex has been based on “Check one: male or female,” many intersex people have not even been aware that they were intersex and thus would have reported the sex to which they were assigned at birth. This is especially important, because those psychological sex differences that have been reported have usually been so small. . . . Keeping in mind that intersex people vary greatly from each other, how might that alter the picture? . . . there is simply no way to know how their inclusion in studies has altered the field (p. 8). Having raised this matter, it is useful to return to it every time research about a new topic is introduced. Depending on the class size, I ask students to give oral presentations during lecture or discussion sections. Each presentation lasts no more than 12–15 minutes. The stu- dent chooses two pieces of research about a particular topic related to sex and gender. One must be better designed, executed, and/or interpreted than the other. The presenta- tion includes a concise but clear description of each study, including whatever listeners need to know in order to un- derstand the critique that the presenter then offers. This exercise provides a good foundation for students in writ- ing the final paper for this course, as well as for writing literature reviews for theses and dissertations. The final essay for the course is a 12- to 15-page paper. I explain that this paper must be very carefully thought out, well organized, and efficiently written. The paper must be based on 8–10 research articles about one topic they choose. They can select these articles in a number of ways, such as two reports from each of the past four or five decades or else the best research reports about the topic that the student can find, combined with the worst. I strongly advise stu- dents before writing the paper to read each of the research articles and take extensive, careful notes using the “How to Do a Critique” approach. This strategy provides a clear view of the strengths and weaknesses of each study and of whether any studies are so seriously flawed that we can learn nothing from them. In writing the paper, students should look for ways to critique the body of studies effi- ciently. For example, they may describe in some detail one, two, or three of the studies and their flaws. Then they can more briefly compare and contrast the subsequent studies to their initial study. Or they may list all of the kinds of problems found in one or more of the studies, and then say which studies include which problems. Where relevant and illuminating, they should also mention studies’ strengths. Crucial to the paper is to compare what each paper’s authors claim their research shows with what—given the paper’s limitations—their research legitimately does show. The paper should end with one or a few sentences that many students find to be the most difficult to write: a “state of the science” statement. This statement is the student’s opinion about what, given the pros and cons of each study, one can confidently say is definitely known about the topic. By the time the reader reaches that final statement, the student’s evaluative descriptions of the research reports should be extremely clear. In fact this final statement should come as no surprise; rather, it should be a crystal-clear digest of the preceding pages. I give a final examination when I teach this material to undergraduates. About one-third consists of short-answer identification items, designed to encourage students to do the reading. The remainder consists of a single essay ques- tion. For the essay, I construct an article that is written as though it comes from a scholarly journal or presenta- tion. This article includes as wide a variety of problems as possible, including (a) citation of previous research with- out questioning its quality or the conclusions its authors reached; (b) biases in choosing the research question; (c) problems in logic when shifting from existing literature to hypothesis or research question; (d) problems in whether the research design follows logically from the hypothesis or research question; (e) problems of various kinds within the design itself; and (f) unwarranted or inadequate inter- pretations of the data. The student’s task is, on the spot, to write a critique of that paper. (An example created with Kathryn Morgan and other instructors is available online.) It is important to include specific instructions on the actual examination that they must not just criticize the authors for not choosing a different topic or for not conducting a larger study. As a result of the elements of this kind of course, stu- dents acquire depth of practice in thinking critically about research on sex and gender. REFERENCES Caplan, P. J., & Caplan, J. B. (1994). Thinking critically about research on sex and gender. New York: Harper Collins. Caplan, P. J., & Caplan, J. B. (1999). Thinking critically about research on sex and gender (2nd ed.). New York: Addison Wesley Longman. Caplan, P. J., & Caplan, J. B. (2009). Thinking critically about re- search on sex and gender (3rd ed.). Boston: Allyn & Bacon. Caplan, P. J., Secord-Gilbert, M., & Staton, P. (1990). Teaching children to think critically about sexism and other forms of bias. Toronto: Green Dragon Press. Fausto-Sterling, A. (2000). Sexing the body: Gender politics and the construction of sexuality. New York: Basic Books. SUPPORTING INFORMATION The following supporting information is available for this article online at http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/ PWQ Teaching Briefs, December 2010 557 journal/10.1111/(ISSN)1471-6402: Caplan, Morgan, et al.’s final exam research critique. Paula J. Caplan, Ph.D., is a clinical and research psy- chologist currently affiliated at Harvard University with the DuBois Institute and the Kennedy School of Government’s Women and Public Policy Program. APPENDIX: HOW TO DO A CRITIQUE 1. Read the article carefully. Read it at least three more times, making notes as you go, about the authors’ claims and the questions that come to mind. 2. Identify theoretical assumptions the authors make. These may be either explicitly stated or implicit. Con- sider whether or not these make sense and seem true. Furthermore, are there any internal inconsistencies within the theory? 3. What predictions do they make or hypotheses do they state? Do they follow from the theory? Are they clearly stated? 4. Method: Was the study designed and carried out in a way that actually allows the authors to test their predictions or hypotheses? Is it clear what the authors actually did in the study? Are there problems with the way the study was designed? 5. Results: Were the results analyzed appropriately? Are the methods of analysis clearly described (either in the Method or the Results section)? Are the results clearly presented? 6. Discussion: Do the authors’ conclusions follow from the results they obtained? Are there any rival hypothe- ses that could adequately explain the results? Note: DO NOT criticize the authors for not choosing a different topic or doing a larger study UNLESS their predictions/hypotheses cannot be tested using the study they designed. Copyright of Psychology of Women Quarterly is the property of Wiley-Blackwell and its content may not be copied or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder's express written permission. However, users may print, download, or email articles for individual use. work_eoql43uylzddhjmndsxriumzpq ---- Race and the Criminal Justice System: An overview to the complete statistics 2004–2005 Section 95 Criminal Justice Act 1991 Race and the Criminal Justice System: An overview to the complete statistics 2004–2005 March 2006 Section 95 Criminal Justice Act 1991 Race and the Criminal Justice System: An overview to the complete statistics 2004–2005 March 2006 ii Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System (1) The Secretary of State shall in each year publish such information, as he considers expedient for the purpose of: (a) enabling persons engaged in the administration of justice to become aware of the financial implications of their decisions; or (b) facilitating the performance of such persons of their duty to avoid discriminating against any persons on the ground of race or sex or any other improper ground. (2) Publication under subsection (1) above shall be effected in such a manner, as the Secretary of State considers appropriate for the purpose of bringing the information to the attention of the persons concerned. This report was prepared by Batool Reza and Christine Magill and published by the Criminal Justice System Race Unit. Further copies are available from: Criminal Justice System Race Unit 2 Marsham Street London SW1P 4DF Email: CJSRACE@homeoffice.gsi.gov.uk This publication is available on the Home Office website http://www.homeoffice.gsi.gov.uk/rds © Crown copyright 2006 ISBN x xxxx xxxx Criminal Justice Act 1991 section 95 Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System iii We, the Criminal Justice Ministers, are pleased to publish this update of the Overview to the Section 95 and CJS statistics. This report summarises the most recent statistics available on race and Criminal Justice and seeks to put in context what this reveals about BME groups’ experiences across the CJS. We want to build a society where there are equal opportunities for all. An essential part of this is for all those organisations responsible for delivering criminal justice to make sure they promote equality; do not discriminate against anyone because of their race; that the people who work for them are representative of the population; and that the system is effective in tackling racism and racist crime. We have made enormous progress in recent years strengthening the legal framework against discrimination, improving diversity training and toughening up our recruitment processes to make sure racists cannot get into CJS agencies, making the CJS more representative of the communities it serves; and improving how we investigate and prosecute hate crime. However we are not complacent and realise we still have a lot to do. These statistics show people from BME communities continue to be over- represented in the criminal justice process and are less likely than White people to be confident that the CJS will treat them fairly. Chapter six of this report outlines the variety of activities we are undertaking to continue to address inequalities. We believe the Overview Report and the Section 95 statistics are crucial measuring tools in moving towards an equitable Criminal Justice System. We will continue to encourage joint working between agencies and communities to deliver an impartial, fair and effective system to all. Secretary of State for Constitutional Affairs Attorney General Home Secretary Foreword by Ministers iv Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System This report provides an overview of the key findings from the detailed publication Statistics on Race and the Criminal Justice System – 2005. It updates the summary of 2003/04 statistics published in February 20051, and looks specifically at what has changed and what has stayed the same. The data reported show that progress continues to be made in relation to the proportion of staff from Black and Minority Ethnic (BME) groups working in the Criminal Justice System (CJS). However, other areas remain largely unchanged with BME groups continuing to be disproportionately represented in the CJS. When interpreting the data, it is important to note that people from BME groups are often disadvantaged in social and economic terms compared to the White population. This disadvantage relates to factors such as housing, education and employment; factors that are in part predictive of offending behaviour and general involvement in the criminal justice process. Data concerning ethnicity and crime needs to be treated with extreme caution2 because the data may be inaccurate or missing altogether (as many crimes may be unreported or the ethnicity of the perpetrator unknown). However, evidence suggests that the imbalance is not simply the result of people from BME groups committing a disproportionate number of crimes.3,4 There is not, as yet, sufficiently robust data and evidence from which to reach definite conclusions as to the cause, or causes, of the disproportionate representation of BME groups observed in the data described. What is clear from the data is that disproportionality continues to be a key issue meriting further investigation. Main findings: Experience as users of the CJS ● The 2004/05 BCS shows that people from Mixed ethnic groups face significantly higher risks of crime than White people. However, there were no other statistically significant differences between people from different ethnic backgrounds. ● The 2004/05 BCS shows that people in BME groups were significantly more likely than White people to be worried about burglary, car crime and violent crime. Summary 1 Barclay et al (2005) Race and the Criminal Justice System: An overview to the complete statistics 2003/4. London. 2 Bowling, B. and Phillips, C. (2002) Racism, Crime and Justice. Harlow: Longman. 3 Sharp C. and Budd T. (2005) Minority ethnic groups and crime: findings from the Offending Crime and Justice Survey 2003, Home Office Online Report 33/05 London: Home Office. 4 Aust, R, & Smith, N. (2003). Ethnicity and drug use: key findings from the 2001/2002 British Crime Survey. Findings 209. London: Home Office ● Racist incidents recorded by the police have continued to rise with nearly 60,000 incidents recorded in 2004/05, although the latest information from the BCS (self-reported crime) estimates that actual numbers of racist incidents fell from 206,000 in 2003/04 to 179,000 in 2004/05. ● There were 37,000 racially aggravated offences recorded in 2004/05. Just over a third of these offences were cleared up by the police – a similar proportion to previous years. ● In the three years 2002/03, 2003/04 and 2004/05, the police recorded 2,565 homicides. Wide disparities in risks exist for different ethnic groups. Black people were 4.5 times more likely and Asian people nearly twice as likely to be homicide victims as White people (excluding Shipman cases). Experience as suspects, defendants and prisoners ● There were 838,700 stop and searches recorded by the police under section 1 of the Police and Criminal Evidence Act 1984 and other legislation in 2004/05. This is a 14% increase on the previous year. ● Black people were six times more likely to be stopped and searched under Section 1 compared to White people, Asian people were as twice as likely to be stopped and searched. These rates are similar to previous years. ● In 2004/05, 41,300 searches were recorded by the police under Section 60 of the Criminal Justice and Public Order Act 1994 in 31 police force areas. ● Black people were 14 times more likely to be stopped and searched under Section 60 compared to White people whereas Asian people were six times more likely to be searched. ● In 2004/05, 32,086 searches were recorded by the police under Section 44(1) and Section 44(2) of the Terrorism Act 2000. ● Black people were 2.5 times as likely to be stopped and searched under the Terrorism Act when compared to White people in 2004/05 (down from three times more likely in 2003/04). Asian people were twice as likely to be stopped and searched under these powers than White people; again down from three times in 2003/04. ● The police cautioned 237,323 persons for notifiable offences in 2004. National cautioning rates were similar for Asian, White and Other ethnic groups, whereas the rate for Black people was almost three times that for White people. ● BME groups were more likely than White people to be committed at magistrates’ court to be tried by a jury at the Crown Court (20% for Black people, 30% for Asians and 15% for White people). BME defendants were substantially more likely to be acquitted at the Crown Court than White defendants (29% for Black people, 30% for Asians and 22% for White people). ● Black young offenders and those in the Mixed ethnic group were more likely to receive a community sentence compared to White offenders but less likely to be discharged or given a referral order. ● Black and Asian offenders accounted for 6% and 4% of persons starting court order supervision, with 2% and 1% respectively accounting for by the Mixed or ‘Chinese and other’ ethnicity. ● Excluding foreign nationals, the proportion of Black prisoners on 30 June 2005 relative to the population five times higher than for White people. Similarly, people from Mixed ethnic backgrounds were more than twice as likely to be in prison than their White counterparts. ● The number of deaths recorded for Black people has continued to fall from 16 people in 2002/03, 7 in 2003/04 to 4 in 2004/05. Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System v Working in the CJS ● The representation of BME groups working for the criminal justice agency has improved in recent years. In 2004/05 the CPS, Police, Prison and Probation Services all recorded an increase in the percentage of BME staff on the previous year. Similarly, the percentage of BME staff also increased in the Crown and magistrates courts. Confidence in the CJS ● People from an Asian or ‘Other’ ethnic background were the most likely to rate the criminal justice agencies as doing a good or excellent job. ● Relative to White people, people from BME groups reported higher levels of perceived discrimination within the Criminal Justice System. Thirty-one per cent of people from minority ethnic groups feel that they would be treated worse than people of other races by one or more of the five Criminal Justice System organisations. This shows no significant change from 2001 (33%) or 2003 (31%). There has, however, been a statistically significant decrease in the percentage of people from minority ethnic groups who feel they would be treated worse than other races in four of the five organisations (the Courts, CPS, the Police and the Prison Service). vi Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System vii Page Foreword iii Summary iv Chapter 1: Introduction 1 Chapter 2: The experience of people from BME groups as users of the Criminal Justice System 3 Chapter 3: The experience of people from BME groups as suspects, defendants and prisoners 9 Chapter 4: The experience of people from BME groups working in the Criminal Justice System 23 Chapter 5: Confidence in the Criminal Justice System among people from BME groups 27 Chapter 6: What is being done? 30 References 35 Contents Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 1 Since 1992 the Home Office has published statistical information to meet the requirement under Section 95 of the 1991 Criminal Justice Act. The aim of these publications is to help those involved in the administration of justice to avoid discrimination on the grounds of race. An additional publication to the 2002-3 statistics was published in July 2004 to present both an overview5 of the statistical information and also a more general assessment of the experience of Black and Minority Ethnic (BME) groups within the criminal justice system in England and Wales. The current document aims to highlight the main national changes that have taken place between 2003-4 and 2004-5 in both the statistical indicators and also in the development of policy and practice. The companion document Statistics on Race and the Criminal Justice System available on the Home Office RDS website includes breakdowns by police force areas. This report presents summary data describing the experiences of BME groups not just as victims, suspects and offenders but also as employees within the criminal justice system. For the moment, ethnic monitoring data are collected using a broad classification system.6 As a consequence, we lack detailed information on the experiences of specific ethnic categories, and on the particular problems, within distinct geographical areas. The population figures used in this report were derived from the mid year 2004 population estimates produced by the Office for National Statistics and weighted using the 2001 Census.7 This showed the proportions of the population aged 10 years and over across England and Wales as 91.3% White; 2.8% Black; 4.7% Asian and 1.2% ‘Other’. When interpreting the data, it is worth noting that people from BME groups are often significantly disadvantaged in social and economic terms compared to the White population, although there is considerable variation between and within each ethnic group. For example, Chinese and Indian groups tend to suffer little or no economic disadvantage relative to White groups; Black Caribbean, Bangladeshi and Pakistani groups suffer a range of severe forms of disadvantage, as do Black African groups, albeit to a lesser degree.8 This disadvantage relates to factors such as employment, housing and education; factors that are in part predictive of offending behaviour and general involvement in the criminal justice process. C h a p t e r 1 : Introduction 5 Hearnden, I., & Hough, M. (2004). Race and the Criminal Justice System: An overview to the complete statistics 2002/3. London: ICPR. 6 The Home Office has commissioned an independent review of how ethnic monitoring data are collected, which reported in 2005.The Root and Branch Review is due to be published shortly and once due cosideration has been given to the report’s recommendations, changes may be introduced in future years. 7 The 2001 Census was based on 16 categories (including Mixed). In order to make comparisons with the population where data was only collected for four groups (White, Black, Asian, Other) the Mixed category was divided between these categories as described in Statistics on Race and the Criminal Justice System 2005 – see Appendix B. 8 Phillips, C. & Bowling, B. (2003) Racism, Race and Ethnicity: developing minority perspectives in criminology, British Journal of Criminology 43, no.2, pp 269-290. Unemployment rates for people from BME groups are generally higher than those from White ethnic groups. There are differences within the BME group with unemployment among the economically active; rates are high for Black Caribbean, Black African, Bangladeshi, Pakistani and Mixed groups and low for Indian and Chinese groups. People from minority ethnic groups are also more likely than White people to live in low-income households. Again, there is considerable variation among the different ethnic groups. Pakistanis and Bangladeshis are much more likely to be living on low incomes. In terms of education, Chinese pupils are most likely to achieve five or more GSCE grades A*-C with Indian pupils achieving the next highest achievement levels. The lowest level of GCSE attainment is amongst Black Caribbean pupils, particularly boys. Black pupils are more likely to be excluded from schools than children from other ethnic groups.9 How ethnicity is monitored in the Criminal Justice System Ethnic monitoring in criminal justice agencies relies on a variety of recording methods and classification systems. Since 1 April 2003 a standard system of recording has been introduced into all agencies based on self-classification into one of 16 categories used in the 2001 Census. This approach allows direct comparisons to be made between criminal justice data and census data. Classification is based around five main groups: White, Mixed, Black, Asian and ‘Other’. The Mixed group mainly includes those of Black and White origin and Asian and White origin. The change to self-classification has been particularly difficult for the police to implement since it has involved collecting data on ethnicity directly from a suspect on the street. As a consequence, a high proportion of data on ethnicity is missing. In view of this problem, the presentation of police data continues the previous practice of using visual assessments and the four groups Asian, Black,White and Other. For other sources, e.g. household surveys (such as the British Crime Survey), prison receptions and the monitoring of those who work in criminal justice agencies, the 2001 Census categories and self-classification have already been successfully introduced. The aim is to introduce use of the 2001 categories across the entire criminal justice system over the next 2-3 years. 2 Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 9 White, A. (2002) Social Focus in Brief: Ethnicity 2003, London: ONS. Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 3 People seek the services of criminal justice agencies for various reasons. The most obvious is to notify the police of a crime but for many it may be as a witness, member of a jury or as a lay magistrate, prison visitor or victim support volunteer. Experience as crime victims The British Crime Survey (BCS) is a large face-to-face household survey asking about people’s experience and perceptions of crime in the last 12 months in England and Wales. It also records whether or not a victim of crime perceived the crime to be racially motivated. In this chapter, results from the most recent BCS, that is 2004/05, are reported. Relevant findings from the analysis of earlier surveys, such as the BCS 2002/03 and 2003/04, are also reported. The 2004/05 BCS shows that there has been a fall in BCS recorded crime in England and Wales since its peak in 1995 (Nicholas et al, 2005). Against this background of declining crime, there are variations in the risks of victimisation experienced by different ethnic groups, as shown in Figure 2.1. The 2004/05 BCS shows that people from Mixed ethnic groups face significantly higher risks of crime than White people. However, there were no other statistically significant differences between people from different ethnic backgrounds.10 The levels of risk for people from White, Mixed and Asian ethnic groups fell substantially between 2003/04 and 2004/05. It should be noted that differences in the risk of victimisation between ethnic groups may be at least partly attributable to factors other than ethnicity. Previous analysis on the 2002/03 BCS showed that people from BME groups were at greater risk of total BCS crime, i.e. household crime such as burglary and theft in a dwelling, and personal crime such as common assault and robbery, than White people.11 However, that was largely explained by the younger age profile of the BME population and the fact that younger people experience higher rates of victimisation. Once age was controlled for the difference in risk between BME and White groups disappeared (Salisbury and Upson, 2004). The analysis of the 2002/03 BCS also showed that people in BME groups were at greater risk of personal crime compared with White people but not of household crime. Comparing risk across the individual groups, people from a Mixed ethnic or Asian backgrounds were at greater risk of victimisation than White people. After allowing for age the difference between Asian and White people disappeared. However, this was not the case for those of the Mixed ethnic group who continued to have higher risks of victimisation than all the other ethnic backgrounds even after controlling C h a p t e r 2 : The experience of people from BME groups as users of the Criminal Justice System 10 Statistical significance means that an observed difference between variables is unlikely to have occurred by chance. 11 The respondent answers on behalf of the whole household in the offence categories of: burglary; theft in a dwelling; thefts of and from vehicles; and vandalism to household property and vehicles. For personal offences, respondents report on their experience of: assault; sexual offences; robbery and theft from the person. The BSC does not cover personal crime against those aged under 16 or against those living in institutions. factors such as age and area of residence. This analysis is currently being updated with data from the 2003/04 and 2004/05 BCS and will be published in a forthcoming Home Office Research Findings.12 Figure 2.1(1,2) Risk of being the victim of a crime (2004/05 BCS interviews) (1) For household offences reported in the BCS, all members of the household can be regarded as victims. (2) For personal offences, the respondent reports only on his/her experience to the BCS. Worry about crime The 2004/05 BCS shows that people in BME groups were significantly more likely than White people to be worried about burglary, car crime and violent crime. In addition, people from Black, Asian, and ‘Chinese and Other’ backgrounds were more likely to worry about burglary and car crime than people from the Mixed ethnic group. Worry about car crime had decreased among White people, and the worry about violent crime had increased among the ‘Chinese and Other’ group between 2003/04 and 2004/05. 0 5 10 15 20 25 30 35 Chinese and otherBlack or Black BritishAsian or Asian BritishMixedWhite 24 29 26 24 23 Pe rc en ta ge v ic ti m s o nc e o r m o re 4 Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 12 Jansson, K (forthcoming) Ethnicity and victimisation; findings from the 2004/05 British Crime Survey. Home Office Figure 2.2 Worry about crime by ethnic group (2004/05 BCS interviews) Racist crimes The experience of crime for those in BME groups, either as a victim or a witness to a crime, will include some crimes that will have been racially motivated. The latest information from the BCS (self-reported crime) estimates that in 2004/05 there were 179,000 racially motivated incidents (including those on White people), which is lower than the 2003/04 estimate of 206,000. Such incidents include the use of racist language, criminal damage and physical assaults. The police record information on racist incidents using a similar definition to the BCS, that is “any incident which is perceived to be racist by the victim or any other person” (Macpherson, 1999). Police statistics show a different result. Racist incidents recorded by the police increased from just over 10,000 in 1996/97 to nearly 50,000 in 1999/00. As shown in Figure 2.3, the number of racist incidents has continued to rise steadily over the last five years with nearly 60,000 incidents recorded in 2004/05. The sharp rise is thought to be the result of encouragement by all agencies and community groups for better reporting by victims and better recording by the police rather than an actual rise in the number of incidents. Although White people experience the highest number of incidents they are at a comparatively lower risk of racially motivated crime.13 0 5 10 15 20 25 30 35 Violent crimeCar crimeBurglary 11 15 27 26 27 12 17 27 30 29 14 31 37 34 37 Pe rc en ta ge w o rr ie d Chinese or otherBlackAsianMixedWhite Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 5 13 Salisbury, H. and Upson, A. (2004) Ethnicity, Victimisation and Worry about Crime: findings from the 2001/02 and 2002/3 British Crime Surveys. London: Home Office Research Findings No 237. Figure 2.3(1) Racist incidents recorded by police forces, percentage change on 1999/00 totals to 2004/05 (1) This figure shows indexed trends. The 1999/00 figure is indexed at 100. The numbers of racist incidents for each subsequent year are each expressed as a percentage of the 1999/00 figures. The 1998 Crime and Disorder Act identified certain offences of violence, harassment and criminal damage as racially aggravated; 37,074 such offences were recorded in 2004/05, of which, 61% were harassment, 24% crimes against the person such as wounding and common assault, and 15% criminal damage. The total number of offences was above that recorded in both 2002/03 (31,034) and 2003/04 (35,022). Just over a third (36%) of racially aggravated offences were cleared up by the police – a similar proportion to previous years (34% in 2003/04 and 34% in 2002/03). This is better than the 30% clear up rate for non-racially aggravated offences. However, the difference between clear-up rates is largely the result of the difference between the number of racially aggravated and non-racially aggravated criminal damage offences. Only for criminal damage offence was the clear-up rate for racially aggravated offences (20%) greater than for the non-aggravated equivalent (14%). For the other offences, that is, harassment, other wounding, and common assault, the reverse was true; the clear up rate was higher for non-aggravated offences than for aggravated offences. Only a small number (4,409 offenders) were cautioned or convicted by the courts for racially aggravated offences. This finding may reflect the difficulty of proving racial aggravation in court.14 60 76 92 108 124 140 2004/052003/042002/032001/022000/011999/00 100 111 114 103 111 124 In de xe d tr en d 6 Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 14 Burnley, E. and Rose, G (2002) Racist Offences – how is the Law Working?: the implementation of the legislation on racially aggravated offences in the Crime and Disorder Act 1998, Research Study No 244. London: Home Office. The Crown Prosecution Service (CPS) also monitors prosecution and outcomes in all cases identified by the police or CPS as arising from a racial incident.15 It identified 5,788 of the cases they dealt with in 2004/05 as being racist incidents, 22% higher than in 2003/04. The police identified 91% of these cases, whilst the CPS identified the remaining 9% (the proportions for the previous year were 90% and 10%). Figure 2.4(1) Defendants received by the CPS, percentage change on 2000/01 totals to 2004/05 (1) This figure shows indexed trends. The 2000//01 figure is indexed at 100. The numbers of defendants for each subsequent year are each expressed as a percentage of the 2000/01 figure. Homicides Murder, manslaughter and infanticide (collectively referred to as homicide) are amongst the less frequent crimes in England and Wales. In the three years – 2002/03, 2003/04 and 2004/05, the police recorded 2,565 such offences. However, there are wide disparities in the risks for different ethnic groups. Excluding the 172 homicides of White people killed by Harold Shipman, Black people were 4.5 times more likely and Asian people 1.7 times as likely to be victims of a homicide as White people, the same as in the three years up to and including 2003/04. 60 80 100 120 140 160 180 200 2004/052003/042002/032001/022000/01 100 120 135 152 186 In de xe d tr en d Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 7 15 CPS (2005) Racist incident monitoring: Annual Report 2004/5 London: Crown Prosecution Service. Figure 2.5(1) Homicides per 10,000 population, combined data for 2002/3 to 2004/5 (1) Number of victims: White 1,750; Black 242; Asian 153; Other 108 (excluding Shipman cases) While the risk for White people was similar for males and females and all age groups, Black victims were predominately young men and a third were the victims of firearms.16 Figure 2.6(1,2) Apparent method of killing of currently recorded homicide victims by percentage, combined data for 2002/03, 2003/04, 2004/05 (1) Those recorded as homicide as at 28 November 2005 (2) Other category includes the 172 individuals killed by Harold Shipman. Sharp instrument 29% 8% 18% 8% 5% 32% 35% 4% 5% 4% 32% 20% White homicide victims Black homicide victims Blunt instrument Hitting/Kicking Strangulation Shooting Other 0.0 0.5 1.0 1.5 2.0 2.5 OtherAsianBlackWhite 0.4 1.8 0.7 2 Pe r 10 ,0 00 p o pu la ti o n 8 Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 16 Bullock, K. and Tilley, N. (2002) Shootings, Gangs and Violent Incidents in Manchester: developing a crime reduction strategy. Crime Reduction Research Series Paper 13. London: Home Office. Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 9 Evidence reviewed in this chapter shows quite clearly that people from BME groups are over-represented at each stage of the criminal justice process from initial contact to sentencing. Evidence also suggests that it is not to be because people from BME groups are more likely to offend.17,18 BME groups’ over- representation in the CJS is not unique to England and Wales. International reviews suggest specific minority ethnic groups are more likely to have contact with the system than majority groups.19 Figure 3.1 Proportion (%) of ethnic groups at different stages of the criminal justice process 2004/05 Criminologists have suggested several factors that might lie at the root of this observed disproportionality, including discrimination on the part of the police20, socio-demographic factors21, the suggestion that Black people spend more time on the streets than their White counterparts22, or police recording practices.23 Another possibility is that those in BME groups committing offences are detected to a greater extent by 0 10 20 30 40 50 60 70 80 90 100 Prison Population Prison Receptions Crown Court Young Offenders Cautions Arrests Stops & Searches Population over 10 White Black Asian Other/Unknown 91 3 5 1 75 14 7 2 84 9 5 1 84 6 4 1 85 6 3 3 76 13 7 4 77 14 5 4 81 10 5 3 C h a p t e r 3 : The experience of people from BME groups as suspects, defendants and prisoners 17 Sharp C. and Budd T. (2005) Minority ethnic groups and crime: findings from the Offending Crime and Justice Survey 2003, Home Office Online Report 33/05 London: Home Office. 18 Aust, R, & Smith, N. (2003). Ethnicity and drug use: key findings from the 2001/2002 British Crime Survey. Findings 209. London: Home Office 19 Junger-Tas, J. & Marshall, I. H. (1999). The self-report methodology in crime research. In M. Tonry (Ed.), Crime and Justice. A Review of Research. Vol 25. (pp. 291-367). Chicago: The University of Chicago. 20 Smith, D.J., & Gray, J. (1985). Police and the Public. London: Gower. 21 FitzGerald, M. (1993). Ethnic Minorities and the Criminal Justice System. Royal Commission on Criminal Justice Research Study 20. London:HMSO. 22 FitzGerald, M. and Sibbitt, R. (1997) Ethnic Monitoring in Police Forces: A beginning. Home Office Research Study 173. London: Home Office. 23 FitzGerald, M. and Sibbitt, R. (1997) Ethnic Monitoring in Police Forces: A beginning. Home Office Research Study 173. London: Home Office. the criminal justice system as proportionally more of those BME groups are likely to be known to the police.24 Other authors have suggested that methodological and conceptual issues make it impossible to conclude that people from BME groups commit any more or less crime than White people.25 The current lack of robust ethnic monitoring data across the CJS, combined with the lack of unequivocal empirical evidence, make it impossible to provide a conclusive answer to the question of the root causes for this disproportionality. However, it is clear from the data that disproportionality continues to be a key issue meriting further investigation. Offending behaviour There is no consistent picture of whether there are differences in offending behaviour between ethnic groups that could explain the over-representation of BME groups. The BCS has asked victims to give their description of the ethnicity of ‘their’ offender. These results show a slight under-representation of Asian offenders, and a slight over-representation of Black offenders. The exception was victims of personal robbery where a Black person was said to be responsible for the attack in about a third of cases.26 Alternative methods of measurement based on self-reported criminal behaviour have their own methodological limitations, so results have to be treated with caution. However, findings from a self-report survey published in 2005 suggested that Black respondents had rates of self-reported offending that were either similar to or substantially lower than White respondents. It found that Black and Black British males in the general population aged 10 to 25 were no more or less likely to have committed an offence in their lifetime than White males of the same age. Moreover, the figures for offending in the last year suggested that Black male respondents in this age group were significantly less likely than White respondents to have committed an offence during this time period. The pattern for older male respondents aged 26 and above differs slightly – the lifetime offending rate was significantly lower in Black respondents compared with White, whilst the last year offending rate was similar across the two groups.27 Stop and searches Section 1 PACE An important ‘gateway’ for some offenders into the Criminal Justice System are the ‘stop and search’ powers granted under the terms of the Police and Criminal Evidence Act (1984) and other legislation. The disproportionate use of these powers on BME groups has been shown both by household surveys such as the British Crime Survey and also police statistics. Although police statistics provide a measure of the risk of being searched, they only record the total number of searches carried out each year and not the number of persons searched. Searches are carried out on only a small minority of the population, but one person may be searched many times in one year. There were 838,700 stop and searches recorded by the police under section 1 of the Police and Criminal Evidence Act 1984 and other legislation in 2004/05. This is a 14% increase on the previous year. This increase is apparent across all ethnic groups. Compared with 2003/04, there was a 15% increase in the number of searches on White people; a 9% increase for Black people, 12% increase for Asian people and 20% increase for people in the ‘Other’ ethnic group. This contrasts with the 2003/04 figures which recorded the first fall in the use of these stop and search powers since 2000/01. The trends in Figure 3.2 10 Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 24 Sharp C. and Budd T. (2005) Minority ethnic groups and crime: findings from the Offending Crime and Justice Survey 2003, Home Office Online Report 33/05 London: Home Office. 25 Bowling, B. and Phillips, C. (2002) Racism, Crime and Justice. Harlow: Longman. 26 Kershaw, C., Budd, T., Kinshott, G., Mattinson, J.,Mayhew, P. and Myhill, A. (2000) The 2000 British Crime Survey England and Wales. Home Office Statistical Bulletin 18/00. London: Home Office. 27 Sharp C. and Budd T. (2005) Minority ethnic groups and crime: findings from the Offending Crime and Justice Survey 2003, Home Office Online Report 33/05 show that overall there has been a gradual decline in the number of White people stopped and searched since 1997/98. Whereas, for Black and Asian people the numbers of stop and searches are broadly similar to levels recorded in 1997/98. Figure 3.2(1) Persons stopped and searched under s1 Police & Criminal Evidence Act 1984, and other legislation, by ethnic group, percentage change on 1997/98 totals to 2004/05 (1) This figure shows indexed trends. The 1997/98 figure is indexed at 100. The numbers for each subsequent year are each expressed as a percentage of the 1997/98 figures. Figure 3.3 shows the number of searches carried out under section 1 PACE for the different ethnic groups expressed as a rate per 1,000 population. In 2004/05 Black people were six times more likely to be searched than White people. This is a similar rate to 2002/03 and 2003/04. Asian people, as in 2003/04 and 2002/03, were twice as likely to be searched as White people. The pattern and level of disproportionality has historically remained fairly constant although, as shown in Figure 3.2, the number of searches carried out by police forces has varied over time. 0 20 40 60 80 100 120 140 160 2004/052003/042002/032001/022000/011999/20001998/991997/98 In de xe d Tr en d White Black Asian Other Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 11 Figure 3.3(1) Persons stopped and searched under s1 Police & Criminal Evidence Act 1984, and other legislation, by ethnic group, per 1,000 population, 2002/03 to 2004/05 (1) Number of stop and searches under s1 in 2004/05: White 626,853; Black 118,187; Asian 59,995; Other 12,901 Number of stop and searches under s1 in 2003/04: White 547,369; Black 108,208 Asian 53,794; Other 10,796 Number of stop and searches under s1 in 2002/03: White 665,232; Black 118,548; Asian 58,831; Other 11,468 Figure 3.4 represents section1 statistics by individual police force areas. The grouping of areas adopts a similar approach to that used in Hearnden & Hough (2004). The areas have been grouped together into four bands on the basis of the total BME population in each police force area. For example, the City of London and Metropolitan Police have the greatest number of BME residents (over 1.8 million) and is the first police force area in Band 1. In contrast, Cumbria has the lowest number of BME residents (just over three thousand) and is the last area in Band 4. The bands are: Band 1 – The six areas with the highest number of BME population Band 2 – The next 12 forces with highest number of BME population Band 3 – The next 12 forces Band 4 – The 12 forces with the lowest BME population. Patterns broken down by individual forces are important, as they provide local knowledge of patterns of disparity, but also illustrate more general patterns of what might be called ‘justice by geography’, whereby the system treats similar people differently in different places.28 For example, within Band 1 the disproportionality in the West Midlands between search rates for Black and White people is higher than the disproportionality seen in London. However, the overall volume of searches for both groups in the West Midlands stand at around half of the London levels. Outside of London, West Yorkshire conducted the highest number of searches in Band 1, however, the disproportionality amongst Black and White people is the lowest amongst these areas. Amongst all the police force areas Northumbria has the least disproportionality between the different ethnic groups, with Black and White people almost equally as likely to be stopped and searched by police. Variations in recording practices in different forces may also play a part in these differences. 0 10 20 30 40 50 60 70 80 90 100 Other Asian Black White 2004/05 Number of searches per 1,000 population 15 13 16 90 83 92 27 24 27 24 20 21 2003/04 2002/03 12 Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 28 Hearnden, I. and Hough, M. (2004) Race and the Criminal Justice System: An overview to the complete statistics 2002-2003, London: Home Office Figure 3.4 Persons stopped and searched under s1 Police & Criminal Evidence Act 1984, and other legislation, by ethnic group, per 1,000 population, for Band areas 1 to 4, 2004/05 Band 1 Band 2 0 20 40 60 80 100 120 England and Wales South Wales Avon and Somerset Essex Sussex Surrey Kent Hampshire Nottinghamshire South Yorkshire Hertfordshire Bedfordshire Lancashire White per 1,000 population Black Asian 17 31 22 6 25 10 12 67 27 19 109 46 3 19 15 91 16 8 7 43 60 16 10 8 18 66 5 33 7 12 14 12 43 16 15 27 90 74 5 0 20 40 60 80 100 120 140 England and Wales Leicestershire Thames Valley Greater Manchester West Yorkshire West Midlands MPS and City of London White per 1,000 population 26 108 34 10 51 20 35 118 45 24 24 107 61 27 9 14 23 87 90 15 27 Black Asian Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 13 Band 3 Band 4 0 20 40 60 80 100 120 England and Wales Dyfed-Powys Cumbria North Wales Durham Lincolnshire Gwent North Yorkshire Norfolk Dorset Humberside Wiltshire Cleveland White per 1,000 population Black Asian 30 48 23 13 69 8 8 26 19 9 96 11 8 72 5 5 11 9 20 75 20 20 11 18 7 14 18 34 18 13 18 18 30 15 15 27 90 17 11 0 20 40 60 80 100 England and Wales Gloucestershire Cheshire Suffolk Devon and Cornwall Warwickshire West Mercia Northamptonshire Staffordshire Northumbria Merseyside Derbyshire Cambridgeshire White per 1,000 population Black Asian 7 34 15 6 46 22 17 44 20 12 10 18 77 20 42 12 11 22 8 37 12 71 36 16 11 14 7 30 13 15 49 25 7 7 34 15 27 90 50 14 Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System There are also wide variations in the reason why such searches are made. Nationally 41% of all searches were for drugs, although in some forces, for example Greater Manchester and Lancashire, the main reason given was for stolen property. Few searches resulted in an arrest, with similar proportions recorded across all ethnic groups. Nationally 11% of searches lead to an arrest for the White and Black groups, 10% for the Asian group and 15% for the ‘Other’ ethnic group. In 2004/05, compared with 2003/04, searches resulting in an arrest decreased by 2% for both the Black and White groups and decreased by 1% for both the Asian and ‘Other’ ethnic groups. Section 60 searches Searches may also be made under section 60 of the Criminal Justice and Public Order Act 1994. This legislation provides the police with additional powers to search persons and vehicles where it is believed that to do so would help prevent incidents involving violence or that persons are carrying dangerous instruments or offensive weapons. In 2004/05, a total of 41,302 searches were carried out under these powers in 31 police force areas, 1,109 more than in 2003/04. The largest increases were in the Black and Minority Ethnic (BME) groups (up 22% for Asian, 17% for ‘Other’ and 5% for Black people) compared with a 3% fall for White people. Figure 3.3 shows the number of searches carried out under section 60 of the Criminal Justice and Public Order Act 1994 in 2004/05 for different ethnic groups expressed as a rate per 1,000 population. The rate for Black people is 14 times the rate for White people whilst for Asian people the rate is six times higher.29 This may be due to the large numbers of s60 searches in areas with high BME populations, such as the West Midlands,30 London and Greater Manchester. Figure 3.5 (1,2) Persons stopped and searched under s60 of the Criminal Justice and Public Order Act 1994 per 1,000 population, 2002/03 to 2004/05 (1) Number of stop and searches under s60 in 2004/05: White 23,246; Black 9,833; Asian 6,844; Other 808 Number of stop and searches under s60 in 2003/04: White 23,868; Black 9,385; Asian 5,627; Other 688 Number of stop and searches under s60 in 2002/03: White 24,179; Black 11,204; Asian 6,979; Other 1,095 (2) Figures exclude vehicle only searches (see Ayres and Murray, 2004/05) 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 Other Asian Black White 2004/05 Per 1,000 population 0.7 0.6 0.5 9 7.2 7.5 3.5 2.6 3.1 2.4 1.3 1.5 2003/04 2002/03 Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 15 29 Calculations based on figures taken to two decimal places 30 Section 60 has been used extensively within the West Midlands under Operation Safer Streets. The proportion of stop and searches resulting in an arrest under section 60 powers varied across forces; overall 3% led to an arrest in 2004/05 compared with 4% in 2003/04, and 6% in 2002/03 (see Ayres and Murray 2004/05). Section 44 searches The Terrorism Act 2000 provides the police with further powers to carry out searches. These powers (under section 44(1) for vehicle searches and section 44(2) for pedestrians) were used to carry out about 32,086 searches in 2004/05, a 9% increase since 2003/04 in 21 police force areas. It should be noted that these figures cover the financial year 2004/05 and therefore predate events in July 2005. Of these searches 23,400 were of White people, 2,511 of Black people, 3,494 of Asian people and 1,481 of ‘Other’ ethnic groups. Two fifths (40%) of all searches were in the Metropolitan Police District and 20% in the City of London. The use of the powers in London reflects the high level of police security as the powers help to deter and disrupt potential terrorist attacks. Figure 3.6 shows Black people were 2.5 times more likely to be stopped and searched under the Terrorism Act when compared to White people in 2004/05 (down from three times more likely in 2003/04). Asian people were twice as likely to be stopped and searched under these powers than White people; again down from three times in 2003/04, whilst the ‘Other’ group were almost four times as likely, similar to 2003/04. Figure 3.6(1,2,3) Persons stopped and searched under s44(1) or s44(2) of the Terrorism Act 2000, per 10,000 population, 2002/03 to 2004/05 (1) Number of stop and searches under s44(1) or s44(2) in 2004/05: White 23,400; Black 2,511; Asian 3,494; Other 1,481. Number of stop and searches under s44(1) or s44(2) in 2003/04: White 20,637; Black 2,704; Asian 3,668; Other 1,322. Number of stop and searches under s44(1) or s44(2) in 2002/03: White 14,429; Black 1,744; Asian 2,989; Other 1,259. (2) Rates expressed as per 10,000 to accommodate the relative infrequency of the use of powers under s44. (3) Analysis calculated using the population estimates for only those police force areas where powers were used. Arrests Seven per cent of all arrests for notifiable offences in 2004/05 resulted from a ‘stop and search’, the same proportion as 2003/04. Figure 3.7 shows the incidence of arrests per 1,000 population for 2002/03 to 0 5 10 15 20 25 30 35 40 Other Asian Black White 2004/05 Number of searches per 1,000 population 9 7 6 22 23 16 20 20 16 34 29 31 2003/04 2002/03 16 Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 2004/05.31 A similar pattern is apparent in terms of disproportionality as is shown above for searches. However, the differences between ethnic groups are not as distinct. Black people, for example, were six times more likely to be searched under section 1 than White people whereas the arrest rate for Black people is three times the rate for White people. Figure 3.7 also shows that arrest rates for different ethnic groups have changed little over the three years. Unlike stop and searches the level of total arrests has remained relatively constant for all BME groups over this time. The difference between the two trends can be explained by the recent fall in arrests for offences, for example drugs offences, that could follow a stop and search in contrast to a rise in arrests for other types of offences. Figure 3.7(1,2) Persons arrested for notifiable offences per 1,000 population, by ethnic group 2002/03 to 2004/05 (1) Number of arrests 2002/03: White 1,102,900; Black 116,722; Asian 64,276; Other 17,250 Number of arrests 2003/04: White 1,122,135; Black 116,427; Asian 63,458; Other 19,092 Number of arrests 2004/05: White 1,142,266; Black 118,579; Asian; 65,905 Other 19,508 (2) Figures for Merseyside estimated. The type of offences that led to an arrest has changed little over recent years. In 2004/05, Black people remained over-represented for robbery offences (29% of all arrests for robbery) and Black and Asian people for fraud and forgery (18% and 11% respectively of those arrested for this offence). Cautions Once arrested, suspects may be charged, given a formal caution, written warning or have no further action taken. For those aged under 17, a caution is in the form of a reprimand or final warning. Relative to population (Figure 3.8), the cautioning rates per 1,000 population were similar for Asian,White and Other groups, whereas the rate for Black people was almost three times that for White people in 2004. There has been little change in cautioning rates and differences between groups since 2002. Looking at the percentage of arrests resulting in a caution, Black people remained slightly less likely to be cautioned than other ethnic groups – only 13% of arrests resulting in a cautioned compared with 16% for Asian and 0 10 20 30 40 50 60 70 80 90 100 Other Asian Black White 2004/05 Per 1,000 population 27 26 26 91 89 90 30 30 29 36 35 32 2003/04 2002/03 Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 17 31 Incidence describes the number of incidents in an area. 17% for White people. When compared with arrests Black people were shown to be consistently more reluctant to be cautioned than White people. A caution or reprimand can be given only where an offender admits the offence, and this partly explains the lower rates of cautioning for ethnic minorities.32 Figure 3.8(1) Persons cautioned for notifiable offences, per 1,000 population, by ethnic group, 2002 to 2004 (1) Number of cautions 2002/03: White 173,273; Black 13,901; Asian 9,918; Other 2, 313 Number of cautions 2003/04: White 1, 85,082; Black 14,720; Asian 10,256; Other 2,703 Number of cautions 2004/05: White 198,847; Black 15,266; Asian 10,511; Other 2,740 Court proceedings Increasingly the police seek charging advice from the CPS. This is under the provision of the new statutory charging scheme through which the CPS prosecutor decides the charge in the majority of cases, with a few minor exceptions. Statutory charging is currently being rolled out across the country and will be fully implemented in all parts of England and Wales by 2007. An initial race and gender impact assessment of charging decisions was undertaken in two parts of London in early 2004 and found no ethnic differential. The CPS is currently undertaking an Equality and Diversity Impact Assessment on the impact of statutory charging to discover if charging decisions vary with the gender and ethnicity of the suspect. The report on this work is due to be published in the first quarter of the financial year 2006/07. At present there are no comprehensive ethnic data on proceedings at either magistrates’ courts or the Crown Court. For magistrates’ courts, ethnic data is only available for six police force areas where the level of missing data is below 20%. The Crown Court has recently introduced an ethnic monitoring system enabling the collection of the ethnicity of 78% of all suspects tried in 2004 (up from 65% in 2003).33 Each year figures are published for only those police force areas with the most complete data, i.e. where the proportion unknown was 15% or less. In 2004, there were 16 such areas. This is an improvement on 2003 when figures were published for only five police force areas. At both courts, court staff extract the 0 2 4 6 8 10 12 14 Other Asian Black White 2004/05 Per 1,000 population 5 4 4 12 11 11 5 5 5 5 5 4 2003/04 2002/03 18 Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 32 Phillips and Brown (1998) Entry into the Criminal Justice System: a Survey of Police Arrests and Their Outcomes, Home Office Research Study No. 185, London: Home Office. 33 For complete breakdown of ethnicity data provided by the magistrates and Crown Court refer to Statistics on Race and the Criminal Justice System – 2005. London: Home Office. ethnicity of a suspect from the charge sheet supplied by the police. The incompleteness of data means that the results must be treated with caution. However the mix of ethnic groups found for Crown Court trials is very similar to that for arrests, suggesting that the data is representative of the population as a whole. Combined information for the magistrates’ courts in the six police force areas is consistent with earlier research34 and the HM Crown Prosecution Service Inspectorate Report,35 which suggests that in 2004 BME groups were more likely than White people to be committed at magistrates’ court to be tried by a jury at the Crown Court (20% for Black people, 30% for Asians and 15% for White people). Earlier research36 suggests that this may reflect the wish of BME defendants to be tried by a jury at the Crown Court. For the Crown Court: combining all available information for 2004 indicates that BME defendants were substantially more likely to be acquitted at the Crown Court than White defendants (29% for Black people, 30% for Asians and 22% for White people). Research by the Crown Prosecution Service37 suggests a tendency for the police to bring charges against Black and Asian defendants with weaker evidence. Sentencing Defendants convicted at either magistrates’ courts or the Crown Court will be sentenced after taking into account information from the pre-sentence report. A small number of defendants will be sent from the magistrates’ court to the Crown Court where magistrates feel their powers are insufficient. The sentencing decision is probably the most complex of all those that are made in the criminal process. Sentences have to take into account the nature of the offence, the plea, the offender’s previous criminal history and other mitigating or aggravating circumstances relating to the offence and the offender. In these circumstances it is difficult to separate differences due to ethnicity against other factors. A major study conducted by Hood (1992) attempted to differentiate ethnicity from such factors and covered decisions made in five Crown Court Centres in the West Midlands in 1989.38 The study concluded that adult male Black defendants were slightly more likely to be sentenced to custody than White defendants, and Asian defendants slightly less likely. It also showed that substantially longer sentences were given to both Black and Asian offenders than White offenders. A more recent study of young offenders (aged from 12 to 17) showed no evidence of significant differences in the likelihood of Black, Mixed race or White male youths receiving a custodial sentence. Asian males, however, were more likely to receive a custodial sentence. Black males, if sentenced to custody, were more likely to get a longer sentence than their White counterparts.39 The data currently available from magistrates’ courts and the Crown Court partly supports the conclusions from this survey although as with the data on court proceedings the results must be treated with caution. It cannot, however, allow for the factors that the Hood study40 was able to take into account since this would require a similar new study. Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 19 34 Barclay, G. and Mhlanga, B. (2000) Ethnic differences in decisions on young defendants dealt with by the Crown Prosecution Service. Home Office Section 95 Findings No 1. London: Home Office. 35 HM Crown Prosecution Inspectorate (2002) Report on the Thematic Review of Casework having a Minority Ethnic Dimension. London: HMCPSI. 36 FitzGerald, M. (1993). Ethnic Minorities and the Criminal Justice System. Royal Commission on Criminal Justice Research Study 20. London:HMSO. 37 John, G. (2003) Race for Justice. A review of CPS decision making for possible racial bias at each stage of the prosecution process. London CPS. 38 Hood, R. (1992) Race and Sentencing. Oxford: Clarendon Press. 39 Feilzer, M. & Hood, R. (2004). Differences or Discrimination – Minority Ethnic Young People in the Youth Justice System, London:Youth Justice Board,. 40 Hood, R. (1992) Race and Sentencing. Oxford: Clarendon Press At the magistrates’ court (for six areas) there was no difference in the use of custody between those from BME groups and White people. However, Black offenders were more likely to be fined and less likely to be discharged compared with White offenders, although the overall use of community sentences was the same. In contrast Asian offenders were less likely to be given community sentences compared with White offenders and more likely to be fined. Community service orders mainly include community rehabilitation orders and community punishment orders. At the Crown Court (for 16 areas) there was a distinct difference in the custody figures for fraud and forgery offences. Forty nine per cent of White offenders were sentenced to custody compared to 70% for ‘Other’ and 61% for Black groups. In contrast there was no marked difference in the use of custody for BME groups and White people for violence, sex offences and burglary or robbery. However, overall Black offenders were more likely to be sentenced to custody than both Asian and White offenders with the highest differences found for drug offences. Eighty per cent of Black offenders were sentenced to custody for drug offences, 74% of Asian and 62% of White offenders. Young Offenders Youth Offending Teams (YOTs), produce the pre and post trial interventions for offenders under the age of 17. Research41 has been carried out on the experiences of BME young people dealt with in this way. This showed that there were higher proportions of young Black people committing some offences and receiving certain disposals than in the general population. In 2004/05, 287,013 offenders were dealt with in this way, of which, 85% were White, 6% Black, 3% Asian, 2% Mixed and 1% ‘Other’. The number of offences has risen by 1% since 2003/04 with the proportion of young offenders in the different ethnic groups remaining largely unchanged. Young Black people were substantially over-represented compared with White people for robbery offences. BME suspects were more likely to be remanded in custody. This could reflect differences between groups in the severity of the charges faced or other factors such as the suspect’s accommodation, previous convictions, failure to appear, inference with a witness, mental health etc. The use of remand has fallen slightly for all ethnic groups since 2003/04 apart from the ‘Other’ ethnic group which showed an increase from 7% to 8%. Black offenders and those of Mixed origin were more likely to receive a community sentence compared to White offenders but less likely to be discharged or given a referral order. Ten per cent of Black and Mixed offenders were sentenced to custody, compared with 8% for Asian and 6% for White offenders. Probation Following the introduction of the 2001 Census categories, information on the ethnicity of persons supervised by the National Probation Service became available. The data reveals that as with other parts of the criminal justice process there is an over-representation of Black offenders. For example, 6% of persons starting court order supervision in the last quarter of 2004 were Black compared to 4% for Asians, 2% for Mixed and 1% for ‘Chinese and Other’ ethnic group. 20 Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 41 Feilzer, M. & Hood, R. (2004). Differences or Discrimination – Minority Ethnic Young People in the Youth Justice System. London:Youth Justice Board Prison Population On 30 June 2005, there were 76,190 people in prison establishments, of which 18,752 (24.6%) were from BME groups42. Nearly two-fifths (38%) of BME prisoners were foreign nationals. Figure 3.9 presents the prison population per 1,000 population for 2004/05. In March 2003 the Prison Service began to introduce new ethnic categories based on the 2001 Census. Due to these changes, comparisons between the figures presented here and those of previous years are not possible. Figure 3.9 shows that, excluding foreign nationals, the proportion of Black prisoners on 30 June 2005 relative to the population was five times higher than for White people. Similarly, people from Mixed ethnic backgrounds were more than twice as likely to be in prison than their White counterparts. In contrast people from ‘Chinese and Other’ ethnic backgrounds were least likely to be in prison, 0.5 compared to 1.4 and 1.5 per 1,000 population for White and Asian groups respectively. The disproportionate number of Black people in prison was, therefore, higher than for arrests although this could be expected from the higher use of custody and the longer sentence lengths referred to in the Hood (1992) study, as well as higher remand rates. Figure 3.9(1,2,3) Prison population per 1,000 population by ethnic group 2004/05 (1) Based on data for UK nationals only. (2) Prison population on 30th June 2005: White 53,645; Mixed 1,746; Black; 6,749; Asian 2,929; Other 168. (3) Proportion calculations based on 2004 Census data for over 15 population. No evidence has been found for any differential treatment of people from the BME group on release from prison. The rate at which prisoners were released on Home Detention Curfew in 2002 have been found to be very similar for White, Black, and Asian prisoners while the rate for ‘Chinese and Other’ prisoners was higher.43 Research on the decisions of the Parole Board44 found no evidence of differential treatment of BME prisoners other than those accounted for by other characteristics associated with release, such as the number of adjudications received during sentence and being housed in an open prison. 0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 Other Asian Black Mixed White Per 1,000 population 1.4 3.2 1.5 7.1 0.5 Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 21 42 This figure includes foreign nationals; of the 76,190 in prison establishments on 30 of June 2005, 10,520 were not UK Nationals. 43 Home Office (2003) Prison statistics England and Wales 2002. London: Home Office. 44 Moorthy, U.,Cahalin, K. and Howard , P. (2004) Ethnicity and Parole. Home Office Research Findings No 222. London: Home Office. Reconviction A study of those released from prison in 200145 and reconvicted within two years showed lower reconviction rates for BME offenders. For example, for those discharged in 2001, 62% of prisoners classified as White were reconvicted within two years of release. For Black, South Asian and ‘Other’ ethnic group, the proportions were 56%, 46% and 46% respectively. However, this analysis included foreign nationals, who record a lower reconviction rate than British nationals as many leave the country after completing their sentence. Restricting the analysis to British nationals reduces the differences found in reconviction rates – White (63%), Black (61%), South Asian (48%) and ‘Other’ (55%). Deaths in police custody In 2004/05 there were 106 deaths in police custody, an increase from the 100 recorded in 2003/04 (Table 11.1). Ninety-six deaths involved White people compared to 90 in 2003/04. For minority ethnic groups the overall number (10) of deaths remained the same as the previous year. In 2004/05, there were three deaths recorded for Asian people and three from the ‘Other’ group. In 2003/04, there were two deaths recorded for Asian people and one in the ‘Other’ ethnic group. In contrast, the number of deaths recorded for Black people has continued to fall from 16 people in 2002/03, 7 in 2003/04, and 4 in 2004/05. 22 Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 45 Home Office (2005) Offender Management Caseload Statistics 2004. London: Home Office. Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 23 This chapter provides information on the representation of Black and Minority Ethnic (BME) groups working for the Criminal Justice System. The number of BME staff working in criminal justice agencies has traditionally been very low. There has, however, in recent years been a marked improvement in representation at all grades in line with targets set for each agency.46 Targets have been set for agencies to reach full representation in relation to the proportion of their staff belonging to BME groups by 2009. Police Service In 2004/05, 3.5% of police officers were from BME groups, compared with 3.3% in 2003/04. This figure is below the representation of BME groups in the population (8.2%).47 In total 6% of police constables with less than one year’s service in 2004/05 were from the BME groups. Asian people formed the largest group making up 37% of all BME officers compared with 26% for Black officers, 25% for those of Mixed origin and 12% from ‘Other’ BME groups. As Figure 4.1 shows the highest increase in 2004/05 compared with 2003/04 has been in Asian (9.6%) and Mixed (11.9%) ethnic groups. Figure 4.1(1) Percentage increase in Police officers by ethnic group 2003/04 to 2004/05 (1) Figures as at 31 March 2004 and 31 March 2005. 0 2 4 6 8 10 12 14 WhiteMixedBlackAsianOther 7.3 9.6 4.8 11.9 1.5 Pe rc en ta ge in cr ea se C h a p t e r 4 : The experience of people from BME groups working in the Criminal Justice System 46 Home Office (2005) Race Equality: Home Secretary’s Employment Targets, London: Home Office. 47 The Home Secretary’s Employment Targets were laid down in 1999 and therefore used the Labour Force Survey as their basis as this was best measure available at the time. In this report, the 2001 Census figures on the percentage of the population in England and Wales economically active and from BME groups are used as a comparison point for representation. Among those ranked Superintendent and above the proportion from BME groups has increased in recent years – from 0.8% in 1999 to 2.2% in 2003/4 and to 2.3% in 2004/05. For those BME police constables leaving the force during 2004/05 the proportion resigning voluntarily was 54% (this was 8% less than 2003/04) however, it remains higher than the 28% of voluntary resignations by White police constables. These differences may reflect the varied lengths of time some officers have been in post. In 2004/05, 6,214 Community Support Officers were in post 14% of whom were from BME groups. This compares to 3,418 in 2003/4 of whom 17% were BME officers. These proportions would have been affected by the large numbers of these officers recruited in 2004/05. There was a numerical increase in the number of BME Community Support Officers from 591 in 2003/04 to 889 in 2004/05. Prison Service The overall figure for BME prison officers in the Prison Service was 4.4% in 2004/05 compared with 4.1% in 2003/04. This is below the 8.2% representation of BME groups in the population as a whole. For Governor grades, the equivalent figures are 3.0% and 3.2%. Black people accounted for nearly one half (47%) of BME prison officers. Eight percent of recruits in 2004/05 were from BME groups. Figure 4.2(1) Percentage increase in Prison officers by ethnic group 2003/04 to 2004/05 (1) Figures as at 31st March 2004 and 31st March 2005 0 2 4 6 8 10 12 14 OtherAsianBlackWhite 4 9.8 1.9 12.5 Pe rc en ta ge in cr ea se 24 Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System Probation Service The Probation Service continues to have representation from BME groups above the 8.2% in the general population. The overall proportion of BME officers was 10.9% in 2004/05, up from 10.5% in 2003/04. This change may have been affected by the decrease in the number of Probation Service Staff where the ethnicity was unknown (the ethnicity of 5.8% of Probation Service staff in 2004/05 remained unknown). The largest percentage increase in the number of staff was found in the Mixed and Asian groups (13.2% and 21% respectively). Overall there was 3.3% increase in the number of Probation Service staff from 2003/04 to 2004/05. This increase is largely contributed to by a 4.9% increase in the White group compared to a 0.4% increase in BME groups. Figure 4.3 Percentage change in Probation staff by ethnic group 2003/04 to 2004/05 Crown Prosecution Service Levels of employment in the Crown Prosecution Service (CPS) are also above the 8.2% BME representation in the population. The proportion of BME staff in the CPS was 11.7% in 2004/05, up from 11.3% in 2003/04. Overall there was 3% increase in the number of CPS staff from 2003/04 to 2004/05. The largest percentage increase in the number of staff was found in the Black and Mixed groups (5.9% and 20.7% respectively). The Other group was the only group to experience a decrease (the groups small sample size means that a fall in the number of Chinese/Other staff from 45 in 2003/04 to 42 in 2004/05 resulted in a decrease of 5.7%).48 The CPS Annual Equalities in Employment Report 2004-2005 states that there is continued progress in improving BME representation at all levels in the CPS. For example, 13% of Chief Crown Prosecutors are from BME groups. Furthermore, 27% of scholars on the CPS Law Scholarship Scheme are from BME groups (a 7% increase from the previous year).49 -5 0 5 10 15 20 25 OtherAsianBlackMixedWhite 1.9 21 3.2 13.2 -0.9 Pe rc en ta ge in cr ea se Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 25 48 These figures are based on calculations including the Unknown category. 49 CPS (2005) Annual Equalities in Employment Report 2004-2005. London: Crown Prosecution Service Figure 4.4 Percentage change in CPS staff by ethnic group 2003/04 to 2004/05 Other Criminal Justice agencies The proportion of BME staff in the Department of Constitutional Affairs was 11.6% in 2004/05. Mixed and BME groups continue to be underrepresented at the most senior levels. For example, for DCA staff at Span 8 or above only 3.8% were from minority ethnic groups. In contrast 14.2% of Span 7 and below were from BME groups. The proportion of Black and Minority Ethnic staff in the magistrates’ court was 9.8% in 2004/05, up from 6.8% in 2003/04. The proportion of BME staff in the Crown Court was 7% – below the BME representation in the population as a whole. -10 -5 0 5 10 15 20 25 Chinese/OtherAsianBlackMixedWhite 2.6 20.7 5.9 5.7 -5.7 Pe rc en ta ge c ha ng e 26 Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 27 This chapter summarises information about the confidence of BME groups in the Criminal Justice System. It draws on findings from two surveys: the British Crime Survey and the Home Office Citizenship Survey (HOCS).50 There is limited evidence on drivers of BME confidence in the CJS. Therefore, findings from recent smaller scale studies commissioned by the Office for Criminal Justice Reform (OJCR) and the Department for Constitutional Affairs (DCA) are also reported here.51 The BCS asks respondents their views on how good a job individual agencies in the CJS are doing. Figure 5.1 shows the results from the most recent BCS (2004/05).52 It found that, in general, Asian people and those from ‘Other’ ethnic groups were the most likely to rate the criminal justice agencies as doing a good or excellent job. For all ethnic groups levels of satisfaction were considerably higher for the Police Services and comparatively lower for the Juvenile courts. Figure 5.1 Perception that the CJS agencies are doing a good or excellent job, by ethnic group 2004/05 0 10 20 30 40 50 60 Juvenile Courts Probation Service PrisonsMagistratesJudgesCrown Prosecution Service The police 48 45 52 52 56 25 34 40 38 42 25 33 44 34 45 27 37 44 34 44 25 31 31 28 38 27 36 35 33 38 16 25 31 28 33 % t hi nk in g go o d o r ex ce lle nt Chinese or otherBlackAsianMixedWhite C h a p t e r 5 : Confidence in the Criminal Justice System among people from BME groups 50 HOCS is a biennial survey, asking a representative sample of 10,000 in England and Wales for their views and experiences in relation to a range of issues, including racial prejudice. There is a minority ethnic boost sample of 5,000 to ensure that the views of this group are robustly represented. 51 These studies are small scale and findings should not therefore be treated as representative. 52 Jansson, K. (forthcoming) Ethnicity and victimisation: findings from the 2004/05 British Crime Survey, London: Home Office However, the most recent HOCS (2005)53 reported that BME groups have much higher levels of perceived discrimination when it comes to CJS agencies compared to the White population. In 2005, 33% of the Black population, 29% of the Mixed and 21% of the Asian group felt that the police would discriminate against them, compared to just 5% of the White population. Similar views were held of the Prison service, the Courts, Crown Prosecution Service and the Probation Service although to a lesser extent. HOCS is used to measure the Public Service Agreement target (PSA2(e)), that is to reduce the percentage of people from BME communities who believe they would be treated worse by one or more CJS agency. Respondents are asked whether they think they would be treated differently than people of other races by the Police, the Prison Service, the Courts, the CPS and the Probation Service. Their responses for each organisation are then brought together into the composite measure, looking at discrimination by any of the five. The baseline for the target is 2001. On the composite measure, 31% of people from minority ethnic groups feel that they would be treated worse than people of other races by one or more of the five criminal justice system organisations.54 This shows no significant change from 2001 (33%) or 2003 (31%).55 There has, however, been a statistically significant decrease in the percentage of people from minority ethnic groups who feel they would be treated worse than other races in four of the five organisations (the Courts, CPS, the Police and the Prison Service) between 2001 and 2005. Change between the perceptions of BME and White people in 2003 and 2005 are illustrated in Figure 5.2. Figure 5.2 Percentage of BME and White people expecting CJS agencies to treat them worse than people of other races, Home Office Citizenship Survey 2001, 2003 and 2005. 0 5 10 15 20 25 30 Probation Services CPSCourtsPrison Service Police 27 23 24 6 5 5 21 17 17 4 2 2 14 13 12 5 6 6 14 12 11 5 5 5 11 10 10 4 3 3 % t hi nk in g go o d o r ex ce lle nt White 2003White 2001BME 2005BME 2003BME 2001 White 2005 28 Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 53 Murphy, R. Wedlock, E. and King, J. (2005) Early findings from the 2005 Home Office Citizenship Survey, Home Office online Report 49/05. 54 The CJS agencies are the Police, the Prison Service, the Courts, the CPS and the Probation Service. 55 Recent analysis has shown that the percentage change from 2003 to 2005 is too small to be statistically significant. Knowledge about the workings of the CJS is one of the factors which may affect BME confidence in the CJS organisations.56 Findings from recent research commissioned by the DCA57 suggest that awareness of the CJS activities is generally lower among ethnic minorities, particularly Asians, than among the White population (based on self assessment of knowledge levels). Similarly a recent MORI study found awareness of the CJS agencies was low across BME groups.58 However, the DCA research also found that Black people were more likely than White and Asian groups to show a strong interest in CJS activities and were also more willing to get involved. Similarly, Asians were more willing than White people to get involved with victim and witness support schemes. In general, BME groups were less likely to have reported a crime to the police and less likely to have any experience of court. Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 29 56 Page, B., Wake, R. & Hill, R. (in press) Confidence in the Criminal Justice System: explaining area variation in public confidence. Home Office Findings 251. 57 Department for Constitutional Affairs (2005) Consumer Experience of the Criminal Justice System, Volume A: Consumer Engagement. 58 BME Communities’ Expectations of Fair Treatment by the Criminal Justice System (2005) 30 Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System Earlier chapters of this Overview report highlighted that BME groups have different experiences and requirements of the Criminal Justice System both as offenders, defendants and victims of crime. The Government is committed to building a society with opportunities for all. A key part of that is a CJS which treats all communities equally, is fair, representative and effective in tackling racist crime. This chapter describes the steps CJS agencies have undertaken to address the needs of BME communities and increase their confidence in the CJS. Criminal Justice System Race Unit BME Trust and Confidence The Government’s public service agreements to ‘Re-assure the public, reduce the fear of crime and anti-social behaviour, and build confidence in the criminal justice system (CJS) without compromising fairness” demonstrates its commitment to having a CJS that is fair and can demonstrate that it is fair to all communities. One of the targets contributing to this objective is ‘to reduce the % of people from BME Communities who believe they would be treated worse by one or more CJS agencies.’ This target requires individual CJS agencies to work collectively to improve BME perception of the CJS by 2007/08. The CJS Race Unit is responsible for guiding and monitoring the work of CJS agencies at both national and local level to deliver this target. Although the target deals with perceptions it will only be achieved if BME people’s experience of the CJS is improved. The work outlined by the CJS agencies in this chapter form part of the delivery strategy which concentrates on improving service delivery, providing information to BME communities and engaging with them to improve their experience of the CJS. Working with LCJBs Local Criminal Justice Boards are at the heart of delivering improved services that will impact on BME people’s trust in the CJS. In December 2005, the CJS Race Unit issued the Fairness and Equality in the CJS toolkit to provide LCJBs with a framework to identify and prioritise actions to deliver the target. This is being followed up by a series of regional seminars to help LCJBs review their current activities to improve delivery. Throughout the coming year the Unit will continue to support and assist LCJBs in working with BME communities and will identify and promulgate good practice. Stop and Search The Stop and Search Action Team (SSAT) was created to provide a joined up response to the problem of disproportionality in the use of stop and search by the Police. As a result of the Team’s work in a number of pilot sites around the country, a guidance manual was issued in January 2005. C h a p t e r 6 : What is being done? The manual provides forces with a template to understand the causes of disproportionality and provides guidance and good practice to remove inappropriate disproportionality. This manual is being developed into Practice Guidance by the National Centre for Policing Excellence (NCPE) with a view to publication in June 2006. In addition Her Majesty’s Inspectorate of Constabulary (HMIC) are now using the key points from the manual to inform inspections. The ultimate outcome of this work is a reduction in the levels of inappropriate, disproportionate stops and searches as well as increased BME community confidence in the use of the stop and search powers. It is disappointing that the activity to date has not generated a decrease in disproportionality however a number of new initiatives will be launched in 2006 including a publicity campaign and a Community Manual to accelerate progress. Developing statistics that drive change If Local Criminal Justice Boards are to deliver a fair and effective system to BME service communities they need to understand BME groups’ experiences of the CJS in their area. The statistics presented in this report are one of the main sources of information available on BME perceptions across the CJS and are a potentially powerful tool in driving performance and race equality. The CJS Race Unit is currently taking forward a major programme of work to improve the collection and dissemination of these statistics. As part of this programme the Unit distributed Race Information Packs to all LCJBs in November 2005. The packs presented a selection of race-related management information taken from Section 95 and were intended to provide Boards with an idea of the range and types of information that is available to inform policy making and delivery. The Unit will use the feedback received from Boards to inform the content of future information packs. In addition to improving dissemination they will also be taking forward work to improve data collection. A key element of this will be developing a minimum dataset mapping out the race related information that needs to be collected across the CJS. This work will be undertaken in consultation with principal stakeholders including policy makers, practitioners and academics. Home Office Police The report of the Stephen Lawrence Inquiry highlighted that BME communities feel unfairly targeted by Police Stop and Search Powers. In April 2005, the Police and Criminal Evidence Act was amended to include the recording of all stops (previously only searches were recorded). The implementation of this recommendation was supported by guidance produced by the Home Office, the Association of Chief Police Officers and the Association of Police Authorities. A further recommendation of the report of the Stephen Lawrence Inquiry was to improve services to victims. The police last year introduced a Code of Practice for the reporting and recording of the racist incidents. A Home Office evaluation of the Code was produced in October 2005. The response to its recommendations will be overseen by a Racist Incidents Group set up by the Home Secretary. The National Community Safety Plan 2006-09 (incorporating the National Policing Plan) was published in November 2005 and confirms the continuation of a priority focus on delivering a citizen focused police service. The police are introducing dedicated, visible, accessible and responsive neighbourhood policing teams in all areas in England and Wales by 2008. These teams will forge a new relationship with local people Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 31 based on active cooperation and engagement. Forces are also implementing a set of minimum service standards that every member of every community can expect from the police service. The Police and Home Office have continued to focus efforts on improving BME representation in police officers, police staff and the Special Constabulary. Prison Service The Prison Service remains committed to providing equal opportunity, promoting diversity and eliminating racism and other forms of discrimination. Good progress has been made with taking forward the action plan, Implementing Race Equality in Prisons – A Shared Agenda for Change. The plan was agreed with the CRE in 2003, and sets out the work that the Prison Service will undertake to ensure full compliance with the Race Relations (Amendment) Act 2000 and embed the lessons learned from the CRE Formal Investigation. This work now forms part of the Prison Service Race Equality Scheme, which was revised during 2004/05. The scheme, which sets out how the service will meet its general statutory duty under the Race Relations (Amendment) Act 2000 duty, was published in May 2005 and may be viewed at www.prisonservice.gov.uk/abouttheservice/racediversity Improvements in the IT programs have enabled greater use of ethnic monitoring data by the Race Relations Management Team, who have developed race relations key performance targets for both staff and prisoners. Race relations audits include: racist incident reporting; ethnic monitoring data; prisoner survey (measuring the quality of prison life); visitor survey; staff race equality audit; staff racial grievances and complaints; percentage of BME staff and percentage of BME staff in contact roles. Since the introduction of the Employment Targets in 1999, increasing BME representation remains critical to the Prison Service. The information, data and analysis produced by the Quarterly Ethnicity Review the Human Resources Planning Team helps to highlight and pinpoint the areas where the Service still has to work harder. It allows for the continuous tracking of progress and efforts made towards meeting the targets set. Representation at senior officer level is not progressing as well, therefore the Service has recently developed a senior operational managers’ programme, which encouraged applications into the management grades direct. The Service is currently developing a positive action programme for its current BME managers and it continues to support BME staff through the RESPECT network. Implementation of the Quarterly Ethnicity Review by the Human Resources Planning Team has enabled continuous tracking of progress and highlighted areas of need for BME focused activities. Quarterly questionnaires on race equality are cross checked against Her Majesty’s Chief Inspector of Prisons (HMCIP) and Independent Monitoring Board (IMB) reports, as well as Prison and Probation Ombudsman reports. Probation The National Probation Service (NPS) has exceeded the Home Secretary’s employment targets for BME staff and has a workforce where 10.9% of the staff is from BME communities. However, minority ethnic groups are still under represented at the senior management level. To address the issue of the low representation of BME staff at senior management level, the NPS has invested in a positive action leadership programme called ACCELERATE which targets BME managers and provides a two-year personal development programme. The first cohort of this programme commenced in September 2004 with 12 participants and is due to be completed in 2007, 25% of this cohort has 32 Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System already been successfully promoted to more senior roles within the criminal justice sector. The ACCELERATE programme was short listed for the Personnel Today award (2005) for excellence in career development. A high priority for the National Probation Directorate (NPD) has been to improve probation monitoring statistics on the ethnicity of staff and offenders. Consequently, meaningful comparisons can now be made between ethnic groups to inform policy and determine the quality of service delivery to BME groups. A target of 95% monitoring for all offenders and staff was set in 2005/06 and was almost achieved with an average total of 94% across the two groups. NPD have incorporated ethnic monitoring into a weighted score card performance monitoring management system to ensure continuous improvement in ethnic monitoring statistics. To ensure that probation responds to the needs of BME offenders the NPD has supported the NPS in developing ‘pathfinder programmes’ for BME offenders. These are currently being evaluated. Crown Prosecution Service The Crown Prosecution Service adopted a new equality and diversity policy and strategy in May 2005. As part of this strategy the CPS has introduced key equalities measures into its Area Performance Review System. These key measures focus on hate crime prosecutions and community engagement. Alongside this a number of equalities themed reviews are being undertaken as part of its performance review systems, including one on workforce representation. A Community Engagement Strategy was agreed in May 2005. As part of implementing this strategy the Service is running 3 community engagement pilots in West Yorkshire, Durham, and Thames Valley. These pilots will be independently evaluated and the findings profiled at a national conference in the autumn of 2006. Good Practice Guidance will also be developed from these. Alongside these initiatives the CPS is also deepening engagement with a range of communities through a series of forthcoming regional information, reassurance and listening events with Muslim Communities. A number of initiatives are underway to further equalities in employment including active implementation of a departmental Diversity Delivery Plan to help achieve Senior Civil Service (SCS) workforce diversity targets by 2008. The CPS is also committed to a programme of impact assessments of key employment processes including a recent impact assessment of Performance Appraisal Box marks rating system. An improved electronic recording project for hate crime data will be launched in 2006/07 and in due course this will be developed further to produce more accessible public reports on hate crime prosecutions. A comprehensive impact assessment of the ethnic and gender distribution of changing decisions is currently being undertaken and the CPS aims to publish this assessment in 2006/07. This involves an assessment of 225,000 prosecutors changing decisions, and will be the largest scale assessment of prosecutor decision-making undertaken to date. The CPS intends to review and update its Racist and Religious Crimes Policy in 2006/07 in line with planned developments on incitement to religious hatred. Alongside this the CPS will keep its training programme for prosecutors on racist and religious crimes under review. Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 33 Department for Constitutional Affairs The DCA is examining whether and to what extent, the courts system deals fairly and justly with the needs of a diverse and multi-cultural society, and whether it is regarded as fair. Two projects already completed are ethnic minority magistrates’ experience of their role and of the court environment, and ethnic diversity and the jury system. A targeted research project to examine the satisfaction of BME users has also been undertaken. The aim is to understand whether the causes of dissatisfaction are related to the service received or determined by other factors and influences such as their age, gender or the capacity in which they were using the court. The DCA is working to increase the diversity of the judiciary through two key work streams: the Magistrates National Recruitment Strategy (MNRS) and the programme of work that came from the consultation paper “Increasing Diversity in the Judiciary” which was published in October 2004. The Judicial Diversity Programme focuses on three main areas; encouraging applications and raising awareness; removing barriers to appointment, and ensuring that the way the judicial office operates encourages and supports a more diverse judiciary. In addition, the Diversity Programme contains four projects of which three have now been delivered. For example, the Developing Policy Project has been developed and is now implementing the DCA’s Diversity Impact Assessment Tool. The purpose of the tool is to ensure that diversity impact assessments and race equality impact assessments are carried out on all policies to check whether the policy could have an adverse impact on different groups of people. Diversity Impact Assessments (DIAs) are carried out on both internal and external policies. Youth Justice Board In the light of the research by the University of Oxford59 a priority of the Youth Justice Board (YJB) has been to reduce the over-representation of young Black offenders. To this end it has set itself the target of ensuring the all Youth Offending Teams have action plans in place: ● to achieve equal treatment at local level for comparable offences by different ethnic groups; and ● to deliver targeted prevention activity that substantially reduces local differences by ethnicity in recorded conviction rates by March 2008. To achieve this the YJB launched, in November 2004, an audit and planning process to address the continued over-representation of BME groups in the youth justice system. This required YOTs’ and their partner agencies to assess the local pattern of BME disproportionality in pre-court and post-court disposals with data on the local BME population. In summer 2005 action plans were submitted from all YOTs, and YJB regional teams will monitor progress against their stated objectives. In addition, for YOT’s that are struggling to make progress, support will be available from YJB performance improvement consultants. Regional workshops will also take place to showcase and disseminate emerging practice. The YJB has also established a Diversity Board that will be chaired by the Chief Executive Officer and will co-ordinate cross directorate activity to ensure effective co-ordination. 34 Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 59 Felizer, M. & Hood, R. (2004). Differences or Discrimination – Minority Ethnic Young People in the Youth Justice System. Youth Justice Board. Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 35 Aust, R. & Smith, N. (2003), Ethnicity and drug use: key findings from the 2001/2002 British Crime Survey. Findings 209. London: Home Office. Barclay, G. and Mhlanga, B. (2000) Ethnic differences in decisions on young defendants dealt with by the Crown Prosecution Service. Home Office Section 95 Findings No 1. London: Home Office. Bibi, N., Clegg, M. and Pinto, R. (2005) Police Service strength, England & Wales, 31 March 2005. Home Office Statistical Bulletin 12/05. London: Home Office Research Development and Statistics Directorate. 29 September 2004. Available at: http://www.homeoffice.gov.uk/rds/pdfs05/hosb1205.pdf Bowling, B. and Phillips, C. (2002) Racism, Crime and Justice. Harlow: Longman. Bullock, K. and Tilley, N. (2002) Shootings, Gangs and Violent Incidents in Manchester: developing a crime reduction strategy. Crime Reduction Research Series Paper 13. London: Home Office. Burnley, E. and Rose, G (2002) Racist Offences – how is the Law Working?: the implementation of the legislation on racially aggravated offences in the Crime and Disorder Act 1998. Research Study No 244. London: Home Office. Councell, R. (2005) Offender Management Caseload Statistics 2004, England and Wales. Home Office Statistical Bulletin 17/05. London: Home Office Research Development and Statistics Directorate. December 2005. Available at: http://www.homeoffice.gov.uk/rds/pdfs05/hosb1705.pdf CJS (2005) BME Communities’ Expectations of Fair Treatment by the Criminal Justice System. London: Office for Criminal Justice Reform. CPS (2004) Racist incident monitoring: Annual Report 2003/4. London: Crown Prosecution Service. CPS (2005) Racist incident monitoring: Annual Report 2004/5. London: Crown Prosecution Service. CPS (2005) Annual Equalities in Employment Report 2004/5. London: Crown Prosecution Service. Department for Constitutional Affairs (2005) Consumer Experience of the Criminal Justice System. Volume A: Consumer Engagement. Feilzer, M. & Hood, R. (2004) Differences or Discrimination – Minority Ethnic Young People in the Youth Justice System. Youth Justice Board. FitzGerald, M. (1993) Ethnic Minorities and the Criminal Justice System. Royal Commission on Criminal Justice Research Study 20, London: HMSO. References FitzGerald, M. and Sibbitt, R. (1997) Ethnic Monitoring in Police Forces: A beginning. Home Office Research Study 173. London: Home Office. FitzGerald, M. and Sibbitt, R. (1997) Ethnic Monitoring in Police Forces: A beginning. Home Office Research Study 173. London: Home Office. Hearnden, I. & Hough, M. (2004). Race and the Criminal Justice System: An overview to the complete statistics 2002/3. London: Criminal Justice System (Race Unit). HM Crown Prosecution Inspectorate (2002) Report on the Thematic Review of Casework having a Minority Ethnic Dimension. London: HMCPSI. Home Office (2003) Prison statistics England and Wales 2002. London: Home Office. Home Office (2004) Offender Management Caseload Statistics 2003. London: Home Office. Home Office (2005) Offender Management Caseload Statistics 2004. London: Home Office. Home Office (2005) Race Equality: Home Secretary’s Employment Targets. London: Home Office. Hood, R. (1992) Race and Sentencing. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Jansson, K. (forthcoming). Ethnicity and victimisation; findings from the 2004/05 British Crime Survey. Home Office. John, G. (2003) Race for Justice. A review of CPS decision making for possible racial bias at each stage of the prosecution process. London CPS. Junger-Tas, J. & Marshall, I. H. (1999) The self-report methodology in crime research. In M. Tonry (Ed.), Crime and Justice. A Review of Research. Vol 25. (pp. 291–367). Chicago: The University of Chicago. Kershaw, C., Budd, T., Kinshott, G., Mattinson, J., Mayhew, P. and Myhill, A. (2000) The 2000 British Crime Survey England and Wales. Home Office Statistical Bulletin 18/00. London: Home Office. Moorthy, U.,Cahalin, K. and Howard, P. (2004) Ethnicity and Parole. Home Office Research Findings No 222. London: Home Office. Murphy, R. Wedlock, E. and King, J. (2005) Early findings from the 2005 Home Office Citizenship Survey. Home Office online Report 49/05. www.homeoffice.gsi.gov.uk/rds/citizensurvey.html Murray, L. and Ayres, M. (2005). Arrests for Notifiable offences and the operation of certain police powers under PACE, England and Wales, 2003/04. Home Office Statistical Bulletin 18/04. London: Home Office Research Development and Statistics Directorate. Available at: http://www.homeoffice.gov.uk/rds/pdfs05/sb2105.pdf Nicholas S. and Walker A. (eds), Crime in England and Wales 2002/3: Supplementary Volume 2: Crime, Disorder and the Criminal Justice System – Public attitudes and perceptions. Home Office Statistical Bulletin 2/04. London: Home Office. Page, B., Wake, R., & Hill, R. (in press) Confidence in the Criminal Justice System: explaining area variation in public confidence. Home Office Findings 251. Phillips, C. and Brown, D. (1998), Entry into the Criminal Justice System: a Survey of Police Arrests and Their Outcomes. Home Office Research Study No. 185, London: Home Office. 36 Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System Phillips, C. & Bowling, B. (2003) Racism, Race and Ethnicity: developing minority perspectives in criminology. British Journal of Criminology 43, no.2. Salisbury, H and Upson, A. (2004) Ethnicity, Victimisation and Worry about Crime: findings from the 2001/02 and 2002/3 British Crime Surveys. London: Home Office Research Findings No 237. Sharp, C. & Budd, T. (2005) Minority ethnic groups and crime: findings from the Offending, Crime and Justice Survey 2003. Home Office online report 33/05. Smith, D.J. & Gray, J. (1985). Police and the Public. London: Gower. White, A. (2002) Social Focus in Brief: Ethnicity 2003. London: ONS. Whitehead, E. (2001) Witness Satisfaction: findings from the Witness Satisfaction Survey 2000. London: Home Office Research Study No 230. Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System 37 38 Section 95 Statistics 2004/5 on Race and the Criminal Justice System This report has been prepared by the CJS Race Unit, and Research, Development and Statistics in the Office for Criminal Justice Reform (RDS-OCJR). Further copies are available from: Criminal Justice System Race Unit 2 Marsham Street London SW1P 4DF Email: CJSRACE@homeoffice.gsi.gov.uk This publication is available on the Home Office website http://www.homeoffice.gsi.gov.uk/rds Contact Points Published by the Office for Criminal Justice Reform. March 2006. Ref: 274134 work_epolg6bp7ve4zhvclssetxuliy ---- Journal ofMedical Ethics 1999;25:137-143 Does justice require genetic enhancements? Nils Holtug University of Copenhagen, Copenhagen, Denmark Abstract It is argued thatjustice in some cases provides a pro tanto reason genetically to enhance victims of the genetic lottery. Various arguments - both to the effect that justice provides no such reason and to the effect that while there may be such reasons, they are overridden by certain moral constraints - are considered and rejected. Finally, it is argued that justice provides stronger reasons to perform more traditional medical tasks (treatments), and that therefore genetic enhancements should not play an important role in a public health care system. (7ournal ofMedical Ethics 1999;25:137-143) Keywords: Justice; genetic enhancements; genetic lottery; end of medicine The chances are that you - the reader of this jour- nal - are a reasonably healthy person. I do not mean to say that you are likely to be perfectly healthy; after all, most of us have some medical conditions that cause inconveniences, lost oppor- tunities or even suffering. However, I think it is fair to say that, as far as our health is concerned, most of us are reasonably well off. But not every- one is so fortunate. Here follows a description of some of the patients at the Children's Convales- cent Hospital in San Diego: "On the beds lie the children - the two-year-olds, the four-year-olds, the ten-year-olds, and the teenagers - some whose limbs convulse erratically, others who are unnaturally still ... "Some of these children will die very young in the bright world of Children's Hospital. For others there will be a succession of hospital rooms, with- out toys or murals, and a succession of nurses, who may no longer wonder how to extend their hands to elicit a response, who no longer wind music boxes, a succession of rooms, to which the children will be largely oblivious. A few will return, at least for a while, to their parents." "In one of the rooms at Children's Hospital, a four-year-old boy who looks much younger than his age sits on the floor playing with a toy. He is afflicted with neurofibromatosis, and his develop- ment was quite normal until a year or so ago, when he suffered a massive seizure, which returned him to a state of early infancy. Slowly, the doctors and nurses at Children's have brought him back, watching him reacquire the capacities of a young toddler. Soon his parents will follow his further developmental steps, waiting for the next seizure, wondering how far he will go this time and how much will be lost."' Some of these children have severe diseases that are due to genetic conditions. They will suffer and, in some cases, die at an early age because they were unfortunate enough to come into exist- ence with a (or several) disease-causing genes. Many of us think that, since they cannot possibly be said to deserve these genes or their vast negative effects, they should be compensated in terms of publicly funded health care services, and perhaps in other ways as well. In the following, I shall spell out in greater detail this argument for compensating people with genetically determined diseases. I shall then argue that, perhaps somewhat surprisingly, it implies that justice may provide us with a reason not only to treat diseases, but also genetically to enhance certain characteristics in people. The reasons I refer to here are pro tanto2 reasons - we have a reason to treat and to enhance. However, pro tanto reasons need not be decisive; they may be outweighed by other, stronger reasons. So the pro tanto reason to enhance may be outweighed by conflicting reasons, pertaining either to justice itself or to some other part of our moral system. There are various ways of drawing the distinc- tion between treatments and enhancements, but I shall take a treatment to be an intervention that aims at curing or reducing the effects of a disease, where a disease is taken to be a departure from species-typical normal functioning. Enhance- ments, on the other hand, do not aim to cure or reduce the effects of diseases. I draw the distinction in this way because I believe that it is at least close to what many people who believe in the moral significance of the distinction have in mind. o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://jm e .b m j.co m / J M e d E th ics: first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /jm e .2 5 .2 .1 3 7 o n 1 A p ril 1 9 9 9 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://jme.bmj.com/ 138 Does justice require genetic enhancements? Since my claim about justice and the pro tanto reason to enhance is controversial, I shall consider various objections and argue that these are not very compelling. Finally, I shall argue that while justice may give us a pro tanto reason for genetic enhancing, it will also (mostly) provide us with a stronger (or overriding) reason not to. This is because more traditional medical tasks - for example, trying to treat severe diseases such as those from which the children at Children's Hos- pital suffer - are more important. 1. The genetic lottery When we come into existence, we do so with a particular set of genes that we have not chosen or influenced ourselves. I shall refer to this distribu- tion of genes to people as the "genetic lottery". Our lot in this lottery is crucial as to how well our lives go. Some are fortunate, others are not. Some are born healthy and with much potential, others are born with severe, painful diseases that cause them to die young. The point of introducing the idea of a genetic lottery is that since we have not chosen our genes, we cannot be said to deserve them. Nor can we be said to deserve the benefits we reap or the harms we suffer because of our genetic make-ups, since neither are due to our choices. For instance, a person who needs an expensive medical treatment because he or she suffers from cystic fibrosis has not chosen to need this treatment or even made choices that cause him or her to need it. Of course, many diseases are more complicated than cystic fibrosis, in that they are partly due to choices. In some such cases, we may be less inclined to say that people are not responsible for them themselves. For instance, what should we say about a case in which a person chooses to smoke although he knows that, because of his genetic make-up, he has an above average chance of developing lung cancer? However, for present purposes, I want to stick to the simpler cases in which people's own choices cannot be said to play a causal role.3 John Rawls has famously argued that we have a pro tanto reason to eliminate inequalities between people that are due to natural contingencies, such as the distribution of genes.4 In fact, Rawls believes we also have a reason to eliminate inequalities that are due to social contingencies, but my focus here is on the genetic lottery. However, as some commentators have pointed out, it does not follow from the claim that inequalities are not deserved that they should be eliminated, or, for that matter, that any particular distribution should be implemented. Nevertheless, I believe that the point that certain benefits and harms are not deserved lends some support to the claim that we ought to redistribute to accommodate the interests of the worse off. Many ofus have moral intuitions to the effect that, when people are badly offthrough no fault of their own, we have a reason to compensate them, for example, in terms of adequate health care services. These intuitions can be accounted for in a number of different ways. We may believe, as do egalitarians, that when inequalities are not de- served we should eliminate them and, for that rea- son, compensate the worse off. Or we may believe, as do prioritarians, that we should simply give pri- ority to the worse off, at least when they are not responsible for so being. Or we may believe, as do utilitarians, that we should aim to maximise the sum of utility and that, in general, compensating the worse off, when they are not responsible for being so, is an efficient way of achieving this aim. Either way, we have a reason to redistribute. And we have a reason to provide health care for people who suffer from genetic defects (and, presumably, for many other people as well). However, the misfortunes that people may suf- fer in the genetic lottery do not stop at diseases. For instance, in a survey of the research done on physical attractiveness and how people are per- ceived it is concluded that: "The social psycho- logical effects of physical attractiveness are perva- sive, strong, and generally uniform in nature. They are such that the physically attractive, whether male or female, old or young, black or white, or of high or low socioeconomic status, receive preferential treatment in virtually every social situation examined thus far."5 Furthermore, other factors with a genetic basis or genetic component, such as intelligence, talent, strength and height, are not evenly distributed. While such features may be less important than health, they are still important for the sort of opportunities a person has. The point I want to make here is that if we are inclined to believe that there is a pro tanto reason to compensate people who are worse off because of their lot in the genetic lottery, there is a pro tanto reason to compensate people whose genes cause them to be worse off because they are less intelligent, less talented, less attractive, etc. The argument presented for compensating people with genetically determined diseases also applies to these other features. One way of compensating people would be by using gene therapy to enhance various features, or by using genetic engineering to produce hor- mones which would have the same effect. Of course, it will be a long time before gene therapies o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://jm e .b m j.co m / J M e d E th ics: first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /jm e .2 5 .2 .1 3 7 o n 1 A p ril 1 9 9 9 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://jme.bmj.com/ Holtug 139 that can enhance, for example, intelligence are available, if this is indeed ever possible. However, today genetic engineering allows us to produce human-growth hormones, and perhaps it will not be too long before gene therapy can be used to make people taller. And there are other, similar cases. Therefore, we have an issue of whether justice provides a pro tanto reason genetically to enhance people to compensate for their misfortune in the genetic lottery. Many people will want to resist this claim and therefore I shall consider various objections, both to the effect that justice provides no such reason and to the effect that while justice may give us a reason to compensate in this way, there are overriding moral reasons not so to do. 2. Justice and distributive units It may be thought that it is only if we hold the dis- tributive unit of social concern to be utility (welfare) that we shall be inclined to favour genetic enhancements on the grounds of justice. While it is true, it may be argued, that people can be unhappy about not being, for example, very attractive, they are not worse off in the relevant sense, that is, worse off in a sense that would make compensations appropriate. However, I believe that on any plausible view of what the relevant distributive unit is, a pro tanto case can be made for genetic enhancements. Suppose that the relevant unit is resources, or opportunity for acquiring resources. Some people make less money than others because they are less intelligent or less talented. Of course, we can redistribute money to obtain a fair (for example equal) distri- bution. But perhaps we can also equalise people's monetary possessions by genetically enhancing people who are less talented or intelligent. So resourcist views do not automatically rule out genetic enhancements as a means of compensa- tion. However, Norman Daniels has come up with a different argument against medical enhance- ments. He distinguishes between treatments and enhancements along the lines suggested above. He then suggests that "medicine has the role of mak- ing people normal competitors, not equal competitors".6 So, at least within medicine, what we should aim at is equality in the sense that eve- ryone is a normal competitor (in the sense of hav- ing species-specific normal functioning), but we should not provide enhancements for people who are within the range of what is normal. Daniels calls this "the standard model for thinking about equality of opportunity". He contrasts it with "a more radical version", according to which "wher- ever possible we must actually try to reduce vari- ance in the distribution of capabilities, equalizing them wherever possible".7 There is, however, some tension between Dan- iels's standard model and another claim he makes, namely that we should "mitigate the effects of normally distributed capabilities through restric- tions on other inequalities we allow".7 So Daniels, if I understand him correctly, claims that if, for instance, some people are making less money because they are less intelligent, or talented, etc, and are not responsible for so being, we have a reason to compensate them, but in terms of social rather than natural assets. Daniels, then, seems to accept my claim to the effect that we have a pro tanto reason to compen- sate people who have suffered bad luck in the genetic lottery, even if the features in question fall within the range of what is normal; however, he adds that compensation for normal features should be dealt with in terms of social assets, and so not in terms of genetic enhancements. But if genetic interventions are appropriate compensa- tion in some cases (that involve treatments) but not in others (that involve enhancements), we must ask what the relevant difference between the cases is supposed to be. As a defence of his claim that medical enhance- ments are not appropriate compensation, Daniels argues that his standard model captures our actual concerns about equality better than the more radical version. However, I do not think that this defence is very compelling. First of all, Daniels compares his standard model to a view that is not very plausible. According to the radical version, inequalities in capabilities should be neutralised. But why should we insist on equalising such differences if there are alternative ways of compensating the worse off that are just as good or even better? Rather, we should aim at the best available compensation, and in some cases this may involve medically improving normal capabili- ties, while in others it may involve compensating in terms of social assets. Secondly, I am not so sure that Daniels is quite right about what our actual concerns are. Suppose that a boy is constantly teased because his ears stick out. And suppose that, from this boy's point of view, the best available compensation would be a surgical enhancement. I am inclined to think that many of us would favour surgery in such a case. Daniels does claim that "we generally resist assimilating these cases of enhancement to cases of treatment because we do not see them as meet- ing important needs".8 However, while we may not want to describe surgery for sticking-out ears as meeting an important need, we would have to be o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://jm e .b m j.co m / J M e d E th ics: first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /jm e .2 5 .2 .1 3 7 o n 1 A p ril 1 9 9 9 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://jme.bmj.com/ 140 Does justice require genetic enhancements? very insensitive indeed to claim that there is no reason to fulfil the boy's desire for surgery. Nevertheless, Daniels may be correct in assuming that we believe that it would be much more important to provide treatment for another boy with, for example Lesch Nyhan syndrome. But granting this to Daniels hardly establishes his claim that, according to our actual concerns, medical enhancements do not fall within the lim- its of justice. An alternative account may be intro- duced, according to which we believe that as far as justice is concerned, there is sometimes a reason to compensate people for their misfortune in the genetic lottery in terms of medical enhancements but that, in general, there is a much stronger though similar reason medically to compensate people who have fared significantly worse in this lottery, in that they have ended up with severe (or even less severe) diseases. I shall develop this idea further in the final section of this article. Finally, I do not think that Daniels really tells us what the relevant difference between medical treatments and medical enhancements is sup- posed to be. He claims that we believe intuitively that there is a difference, but this is an intuition that may have to be rejected if it turns out that, like many other firmly held moral views, it is baseless. This becomes particularly acute in his own exam- ple of two boys, both of whom, it is predicted, will attain an adult height of 160 cm. One, however, has a growth-hormone deficiency resulting from a brain tumour, while the other has short parents and is short because of his (normal) genotype. As Daniels remarks, while the causes of their shortness may be different, they both suffer the same undeserved disadvantages in a "heightist" society, and they are both victims of the natural biological lottery. So how can it be right to treat these two cases differently? Another suggestion as to why justice does not require genetic enhancements comes from Allen Buchanan. Buchanan defends a principle of justice according to which "other things being equal, no person should be barred from the chance to have a minimally decent life as a result of undeserved natural (or social) deficits".9 So disadvantages resulting from the genetic lottery do not require compensation unless they preclude people from reaching a certain decent minimum. Assuming, then, that the genetic disadvantages that might "require" enhancements are generally not severe enough to preclude people from reach- ing this minimum, we generally do not have a rea- son to perform enhancements. (Actually, this is not quite right. There are people who fall below the minimum for [wholly or partly] independent reasons, but who can nevertheless be raised by performing genetic enhancements). Buchanan may either be claiming that, once the decent minimum is reached, justice does not pro- vide a pro tanto reason to improve a person's con- dition, or claiming that, all told, justice provides no reason to so improve. Since I am presently concerned with pro tanto reasons, I shall address the former claim, although this might not be what Buchanan has in mind. So the question is, does justice provide a pro tanto reason to raise people above the minimal level? I, myself, find it very difficult to understand why one should be troubled by a disadvantage that precludes a person from reaching the minimum, but not at all by a disadvantage that is compatible with reaching it. Changes in a person's level of benefits may be very gradual, and to suggest a particular level where her disadvantage no longer matters seems arbitrary. Why should our concern for disadvantaged individuals suddenly pop out of existence once the minimum is met? Of course, there is an issue of what counts as a decent minimum. The higher the minimum, the more plausible it may seem that there is no (not even a pro tanto) reason to compensate people who have reached it. But note that the higher the minimum, the larger the amount of cases in which people are prevented from reaching it due to fea- tures that have nothing to do with diseases. Buchanan does acknowledge that we may believe that it would be a good thing to provide benefits to people who already have a minimally decent life, but goes on to claim that the reason to do so need have nothing to do with justice.'0 However, it seems to me that the reason to provide such benefits is (sometimes) of the very same kind as the reason to provide benefits to people with, for example, cystic fibrosis - people have been dis- advantaged in the genetic lottery through no fault of their own. Rather, as I shall suggest in the final section, there is always a reason to compensate people who have been disadvantaged in the genetic lottery, but this reason can be outweighed by more urgent reasons to compensate people who have suffered greater disadvantages. So while there is sometimes a pro tanto reason to perform genetic enhance- ments, these will (mostly) be outweighed by stronger reasons to perform other medical tasks instead. 3. The end ofmedicine Perhaps there are other reasons, outside the realm of justice, why we should resist medical enhance- ments. It has been suggested that such enhance- ments do not comply with the end of medicine o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://jm e .b m j.co m / J M e d E th ics: first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /jm e .2 5 .2 .1 3 7 o n 1 A p ril 1 9 9 9 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://jme.bmj.com/ Holtug 141 and, for that reason, are suspect. Here, one advo- cate of this view, David Hyman, addresses the issue of cosmetic surgery: "Cosmetic surgery ... collapses the distinction between health and the wishes or happiness of the patient. ... Necessity, requiring intervention, is constituted in the disease rather than in the patient's expressed desires. ... The physician's privilege to refuse to intervene is predicated on a consistent goal of health. ... Medicine is debased as it becomes the handmaiden of vanity and self- indulgence, in the name of 'being your best'."'II The core idea seems to be that medicine has an identifiable goal or end, and that this end establishes the limits as to what goals medicine ought to be used to achieve. This end is defined in terms of "a consistent goal of health". So whereas medicine should be used to treat diseases, it should not be used to enhance normal features in people. There is an issue here of whether the end of medicine can really be restricted to a consistent goal of health. Many of the tasks that are currently dealt with within medicine do not accurately fit this description. Consider, for instance, abortions or surgery for projecting ears. In any case, there is a more serious objection to Hyman's view. Let us, for the sake of argument, grant him that medicine has a well-defined goal or end. Why then should medicine not be used also to promote other ends? Consider this analogy. School-teachers are trained to educate children. But it is hardly plausible to argue that, for this reason, they ought not to use their skills to write poetry. More technically, the "consistent goal of health" to which Hyman refers can be interpreted as a descriptive notion that somehow captures the way that medicine is actually practised. In which case, we are left wondering why this notion should say anything about how medicine ought to be used. Or it can be interpreted as a (partly) evalua- tive notion, that says something about the proper aims of medicine; but then we need an explana- tion of why the evaluative features captured in this notion that rule out medical enhancements are valid or important. And while I cannot rule out that such an explanation can be given, I have yet to see a plausible suggestion as to how it might work. 4. The doctrine of correcting and enhancing in medicine It may be argued that I have not done justice to our actual moral intuitions about genetic en- hancements. When discussing Daniels's standard model, I considered the view that justice or fairness does not require enhancements; I now want to consider the issue of whether there are other moral values that might be brought into play, that would speak against such a medical practice. Consider: The Doctrine of Treating and Enhancing in Medicine Medical treatments are inherently more impor- tant than medical enhancements. This doctrine is intended to capture some important moral intuitions, for example to the effect that there is a moral difference between using genetic engineering to treat cystic fibrosis and using it to enhance a person's (normal) height. Note that the doctrine claims that treating is inherently more important, and not that it is more important because it has better conse- quences. I have deliberately made the doctrine rather vague, in that it does not specify to what extent medical treatments are more important or urgent than enhancements. It is both compatible with an absolute constraint against medical enhancements and with the claim that enhancements are only slightly less important than treatments, although, in order for it to have any real force, presumably it must claim that enhancements are significantly less important. Furthermore, I suppose that some adherents of this doctrine will want to claim that while medical treatments have a positive moral value, medical enhancements have a negative moral value. However, I believe that this doctrine does not adequately capture our intuitions. The standard way of testing such doctrines is to come up with two cases that differ only regarding the factor that the doctrine claims to be morally important, in our case, treatments versus enhancements. So consider the following two cases.'2 Jane is infected with HIV and she is about to develop AIDS. However, there is a new kind of gene therapy available that will boost her immune system - bring it back to normal - and so ensure that she never develops this disease. By giving her the therapy, we would be providing a treatment, since we would be bringing her immune system back to normal. In our second case, Helen has not yet been infected with HIV but, since she is a haemophiliac and since blood reserves at the hospital have not been screened for HIV, it is only a matter of time before she is infected, unless, that is, a new sort of gene therapy is performed on her that will make her immune. By giving her the therapy we would be enhancing her immune system, since we would o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://jm e .b m j.co m / J M e d E th ics: first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /jm e .2 5 .2 .1 3 7 o n 1 A p ril 1 9 9 9 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://jme.bmj.com/ 142 Does justice require genetic enhancements? be giving her a desirable property that people do not normally (or naturally) have. Intuitively, it does not seem less important to provide the gene therapy for Helen than to provide (the other kind of) gene therapy for Jane. But this is what the doctrine of treating and enhancing in medicine says is the case. Therefore, this doctrine does not really capture our intuitions about treating and enhancing. I need to make two remarks about my argument against the doctrine of treating and enhancing. Firstly, since I first introduced the cases of Jane and Helen, evidence has been put forward in sup- port of the claim that perhaps some people have genotypes that make it less likely that they will be infected with HIV. Perhaps they are even immune. This evidence may threaten my claim that people do not normally or naturally have the desirable features that Helen may acquire. However, suppose no one had such features. Would that really make a difference as to how we should mor- ally evaluate Helen's therapy? I very much doubt it. Secondly, note that I am not in my argument using what Shelly Kagan has called a contrast argument."3 In a contrast argument, it is argued that if two cases only differ regarding one factor, and there is a moral difference between them, then the moral difference can be attributed to the differing factor, and this factor will then make a moral difference in any two cases that differ regarding it. Alternatively, if the two cases do not differ morally, then the factor never makes a moral difference. However, as Kagan points out, a factor may make a moral difference sometimes but not always (depending on which other factors are present). I am not using this kind of argument since I am not arguing that it can never make a moral difference whether a therapy is a treatment or an enhancement. I am arguing that since it does not always make a moral difference, the doctrine of treating and enhancing cannot be right. Admit- tedly, since I do not argue that it never inherently matters whether a treatment or an enhancement is performed, my argument is limited, but that is inevitable. Perhaps a different definition of "treatment" would confer greater plausibility on the doctrine of treating and enhancing. Above, I took a treatment to be an intervention that aims at curing or reducing the effects of a disease, where a disease is taken to be a departure from species- typical normal functioning. However, this defini- tion may be broadened to include the prevention of diseases as well. Since Helen's therapy will pre- vent her from being infected with HIV, it should not be considered an enhancement but merely an instance of disease-preventing treatment. But then recall Daniels's case of the two boys who are both predicted to be very short, one because of a growth-hormone deficiency, the other because of his (normal) genotype. If we were to provide growth hormones for the second child, we would not be providing a treatment, even according to our new definition. But why should that matter? Both bQys have a disadvantage (in a heightist society) they have not deserved because of their misfortune in the natural lottery. While it may matter that neither is responsible for the cause of his disadvantage, it does not seem to matter what the exact cause is - rather, it is the effect, and the fact that they are not responsible for it that matters. 5. Justice in health care To sum up, I have argued that a plausible and influential line of reasoning that supports com- pensating people who have severe diseases be- cause of their misfortune in the genetic lottery also speaks in favour of genetic enhancements. Justice requires genetic enhancements in the sense that it provides a pro tanto reason to make such enhancements available to (some) victims of the genetic lottery. Furthermore, I have argued that such enhancements cannot be ruled out on the basis of the claim that they do not conform to the end of medicine or by appealing to the doctrine of treating and enhancing in medicine, since neither of these invoke values that are very plausible. However, while justice provides us with a pro tanto reason to perform genetic enhancements, it also provides us with reasons to perform other tasks, such as providing medical care for people with serious diseases such as the four-year-old boy in Children's Hospital, and even for people with less serious diseases. Since the amount of resources available in the health care system or, in general, for compensating victims of the genetic lottery, is limited (even if we throw in extra resources, this is still the case), we shall have to prioritise. And, although I cannot argue this point here, I believe that when prioritising, we should give priority to the worse off."4 It simply matters more to provide benefits for the worse off than for the better off. Therefore, in general, it matters more to provide health care services for people with serious diseases than to provide genetic enhancements. But, of course, there may be exceptions. Maybe a child who is very unhappy about being short, as in Daniels's example, is a case in point. Maybe it is as urgent to provide a growth hormone for this child as it is to provide medical treatment for a o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://jm e .b m j.co m / J M e d E th ics: first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /jm e .2 5 .2 .1 3 7 o n 1 A p ril 1 9 9 9 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://jme.bmj.com/ Holtug 143 person who has, say, a broken wrist. Obviously, though, we cannot answer this question ad- equately if we do not know the proper unit of social concern, and space does not allow me to discuss this issue here. So let me merely point out that I have already provided a reason to believe that, on any plausible view on what the proper unit is, there will be a pro tanto case for medical enhancements. A further issue that would have to be consid- ered, though, is what the long term effects would be of giving to certain children, for example, growth hormones, or appropriate kinds of gene therapy. It may be argued that giving in to height- ist ideals in this way will just further intolerant attitudes in society and so, even if we restrict our- selves to the issue of justice, such medical enhancements will be counter-productive in the long run. This is a legitimate worry, but one based on predictions very difficult to assess. How, exactly, will medical enhancements affect social attitudes? Another worry about long term effects that has received a great deal of attention is the risk of a slippery slope. I discuss this in some detail elsewhere. 15 These are difficult issues, and I cannot discuss them further here. However, I believe I have pro- vided a case for the claim that justice sometimes gives us a pro tanto reason for making genetic enhancements available; however, I have also sug- gested that, since justice generally gives us stronger reasons to perform other tasks such as providing treatments for people with severe diseases, perhaps, at the end of the day, genetic enhancements should not play an important role within publicly funded health care. What role, if any, they should play in private health clinics is a complicated matter that, again, I cannot address here. Acknowledgements I would like to thank Roger Crisp, Klemens Kap- pel, Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen and Julian Savu- lescu for helpful comments on an earlier version of this article. Nils Holtug, PhD, is Assistant Professor in the Department of Philosophy, University of Copenhagen, Denmark. References and notes 1 Kitcher P. The lives to come. The genetic revolution and human possibilities. London: The Penguin Press, 1996:13-14. 2 The term pro tanto reason was introduced into modern moral philosophy by Shelly Kagan, who writes: "A pro tanto reason has genuine weight, but nonetheless may be outweighed by other considerations. Thus, calling a reason a pro tanto reason is to be distinguished from calling it a prima facie reason, which I take to involve an epistemological qualification: a prima facie reason appears to be a reason, but may actually not be a reason at all, or may not have weight in all cases it appears to. In con- trast a pro tanto reason is a genuine reason - with actual weight - but it may not be a decisive one in actual cases." The limits of morality. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1989: 17. The important point which is relevant for the paper is that a pro tanto reason is a genuine reason, but may be outweighed by other stronger reasons (like my reason to go shopping may be outweighed by my stronger reason to finish my paper). 3 I consider the issues of responsibility and justice in more com- plicated cases that involve choices, in Holtug N. Genetic knowledge in a just society. In: Thompson A, Chadwick R, eds. Genetic information: acquisition, access, and control. New York: Plenum Publishing Corporation (in press). 4 Rawls J. A theory of justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1971: 65-80. 5 Bersheid E, Gangestad S. The social psychological implications of facial physical attractiveness. Clinics in Plastic Surgery 1982; 9:290. 6 Daniels N. The genome project, individual differences, and just health care. In Murphy TF, Lappe MA, eds. justice and the human genome project. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1994:122. 7 See reference 6:125. 8 See reference 6:126. 9 Buchanan A. Equal opportunity and genetic intervention. Social philosophy and Policy 1995;12:129. 10 See reference 9:130. 11 Hyman DA. Aesthetics and ethics:the implications of cosmetic surgery. Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 1990;33: 193,197,201. 12 See also Holtug N. Creating and patenting new life forms. In: Singer P, Kuhse H, eds. A companion to bioethics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1998. 13 Kagan S. The additive fallacy. In: Fischer JM, Ravizza M, eds. Ethics. Problems and principles. Fort Worth: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich College Publishers, 1992. 14 See Parfit D. Equality or priority? The Lindley lecture 1991, University of Kansas, 1995, and reference 3. 15 Holtug N. Human gene therapy: down the slippery slope? Bioethics 1993;7: 402-19. o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://jm e .b m j.co m / J M e d E th ics: first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /jm e .2 5 .2 .1 3 7 o n 1 A p ril 1 9 9 9 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://jme.bmj.com/ work_erkrdoxn5vfnvah553escyzyna ---- NimbusRomNo9L-Regu This is an Open Access document downloaded from ORCA, Cardiff University's institutional repository: http://orca.cf.ac.uk/101431/ This is the author’s version of a work that was submitted to / accepted for publication. Citation for final published version: Moragues Faus, Ana 2017. Problematising justice definitions in public food security debates: towards global and participative food justices. Geoforum 84 , pp. 95-106. 10.1016/j.geoforum.2017.06.007 file Publishers page: https://doi.org/10.1016/j.geoforum.2017.06.007 Please note: Changes made as a result of publishing processes such as copy-editing, formatting and page numbers may not be reflected in this version. For the definitive version of this publication, please refer to the published source. You are advised to consult the publisher’s version if you wish to cite this paper. This version is being made available in accordance with publisher policies. See http://orca.cf.ac.uk/policies.html for usage policies. Copyright and moral rights for publications made available in ORCA are retained by the copyright holders. 1 Problematising justice definitions in public food security debates: towards global and participative food justices Ana Moragues-Faus In: Geoforum 2 Problematising justice definitions in public food security debates: towards global and participative food justices. In the current environment of austerity, social justice concerns are increasingly permeating the food security agenda. However, there is a need to clarify what it means to create socially just food systems conceptually and practically. To address this gap, this paper proposes an analytical framework to embed a more complex conceptualisation of justice in food security debates that also serves as a bridging device across competing narratives. This framework is mobilised to analyse the framing process of the UK media, which plays a key role in developing narratives that provide audiences with schemas for interpreting events. Results show the emergence of eleven frames which highlight different solutions to deliver food security. The application of the justice analytical framework evidences the contingent relationship between food security and justice claims and discusses how these food security frames address differently what counts as a matter of justice (including economic, socio-cultural and political dimensions) and who counts as a subject of justice, tackling issues around delimitation of scales and sites of justice. The analysis reveals polarised positions between whether the sites subject to justice should be individuals or structures and uncovers how political and global elements of justice are largely by-passed in food security debates. These conceptualisations of justice and associated policy recommendations neglect the potential for people to participate fully in the conditions and decisions that give rise to particular distributions of goods and bads in the first place; limiting the construction of shared responsibilities to deliver global and participative food justices. Key words: justice, food security, global food justice, frames, media, participative approaches 1 . I n t r o d u c t i o n Rising levels of obesity sitting alongside staggering undernutrition numbers situate food insecurity - or the inability of people to regularly access sufficient nutritious and culturally acceptable food – as one of the main social challenges of our time. Increasingly, the delivery of good food for all has been regarded as impossible without social justice (Cadieux and Slocum, 2015:3). Given the multifaceted processes and the complexity that 3 characterises food security dynamics, developing a successfully resilient and equitable global food system requires high levels of interaction between diverse stakeholders and a commitment to flexibility and learning in order to produce effective collective responses (Misselhorn et al., 2012). However, so far, solutions and conceptualisations - envisaged from policy, academic spheres and lobby groups - have mostly revolved around oppositional narratives (e.g. efficiency vs sufficiency, productivist vs demand-led) reproducing old dichotomies (e.g. production vs consumption, rural vs urban, local vs global, protectionism vs free trade, etc.) that are unable to address the systemic nature of the global food crisis and its unjust outcomes (Freibauer et al., 2011; Sonnino et al., 2014; Lang and Barling, 2012). This paper explores further how these competing food security narratives support or hinder the creation of socially just food systems conceptually and practically. Recently, there has been a growing body of work around food security framings that aims to unblock this polarised debate and gain an in-depth understanding of narrative formation and its policy implications. Framing is to select some aspects of a perceived reality and make them more salient in a communicating text, in such a way as to promote a particular problem definition, causal interpretation, moral evaluation, and/or treatment recommendation Entman, 1993: 52). Of particular interest is Mooney and Hunt's (2009) examination of food security as a consensus frame - that is, as a term that finds broad acceptance and consent but that is used to make different claims which result in divergent policy positions to address food insecurity. These can range from supporting genetic engineered technology to advocating for land reform. In the UK context, Kirwan and Maye (2013) use the food security consensus frame to scrutinise the relationship between scale and framing, paying particular attention to the polarisation between the official UK discourse – which supports sustainable intensification, market liberalisation and risk management policies (see also MacMillan & Dowler 2012) - and the side-lined proposals of local food systems advocates. These studies highlight how food security discourses have the capacity to produce social realities (see also Nally, 2014), which then translate into targets for policy interventions having implications for people s wellbeing (Sonnino et al., 2016). Despite the insights gained from previous framing analysis, an emerging food security agenda is calling for an examination of the relationality and potential convergence of 4 different narratives and associated interests in order to deliver good food for all (Jarosz, 2014; Hopma and Woods, 2014). For example, Sonnino et al (2016) recently analyse the distinct governance frameworks embedded in food security narratives in order investigate their potential integration. However, there is a need to explore further key concepts that can serve as bridging devices in the entrenched food security debate, and how those concepts are mobilised across different constituencies and deliberation spaces (i.e. academia, policy arenas, social movements and the general public). In this paper, I contribute to this agenda by focusing on social justice, a concept that has recently being recognised as one of the necessary starting points to analyse, and explore solutions to, food insecurity (Cadiex and Slocum, 2015: 3). Furthermore, in the context of economic crisis and austerity measures, both food security and social justice have also become more prominent in public debates of developed countries such as the UK, fuelled by reported increases in food poverty and inequality (see for example Oxfam and Church Action, 2013; Kneafsey et al., 2013). Particularly, social justice has become a fuzzy and ubiquitous word to qualify food poverty or food security challenges, seldom defined in the academic literature, policy arenas or media outlets. For example, Godfray et al (2010:818) state in an agenda setting Science paper that the food security challenge now also requires the delivery of social justice outcomes. Similarly, the European Commission (2010:1) argues that global health improvement depends on greater social justice ; or as Oxfam (2013:7) puts it, the answer to hunger and poverty it s simply justice . The limited engagement of these assertions with the rich literature on (social) justice1 poses a risk of generating a new consensus frame where justice is invoked as an abstract call for fairness. As Loo (2014) identifies, scholars efforts have been concentrated in understanding distributive food disparities leading to a narrow conceptualisation of justice that tends to by-pass the root causes of inequality. By unpicking the connections between food security and the justice literature, through this piece of research I set out to address recent calls for a more rigorous scholarship that engages in clarifying what it means to create socially just food systems (Cadieux and Slocum, 2015). 1 In many cases authors such as Fraser and Young use indistinctively the notion of justice and social justice. There are authors who advocate the use of justice when applied to individuals and social justice when referring to society. In this paper I use justice in order to integrate all the possible subjects and matters of justice. 5 This paper aims to problematise the concept of justice in order to foster progress in current food security debates. The main objective of this piece of work is to embed a more complex and reflexive conceptualisation of justice that allows critical evaluation of existing narratives and provides new elements to help in unblocking entrenched food policy positions. Questions such as what are the different conceptualisations of justice in food security debates, how different food security narratives converge and diverge around particular justice dimensions, and how these distinct justice definitions underpin support for particular policy solutions; are instrumental to assessing the potential contribution of notions of justice to the food security agenda. For that purpose, section two presents a literature review on justice and its intersections with food security, outlining an analytical framework to examine key elements in the process of constructing justice definitions. This framework illustrates the way in which different perspectives address what counts as a matter of justice (including economic, socio-cultural and political dimensions) and who counts as a subject of justice, tackling issues around delimitation of scales and sites of justice. In order to understand how different justice definitions are mobilised, I apply this analytical framework to the UK public food security debate. The analysis of media outlets constitutes an innovation given the lack of food security frame analysis of non-policy communications (with some exceptions, see Wells and Caraher(2014)). Furthermore, the mass media constitutes a key framing actor (see Herman and Chomski, 1988), actively intervening in people s environment by creating public narratives that provide audiences with schemas for interpreting events, that is, framings (Iyengar, 1994; Pan and Kosicki, 1993). For example, Sampei & Aoyagi-Usui (2009) found a direct correlation between newspaper coverage on climate change and an increase of awareness of the public, which was instrumental in the implementation of environmental policies by the Japanese government to cut emissions. The framing and presentation of events and news in the mass media can thus systematically affect how recipients of the news come to understand these events galvanising support for specific policies or interventions. Or in other words, frames influence opinions by stressing specific values, facts, and other considerations, endowing them with greater apparent relevance to the issue than they might appear to have under an alternative frame (Nelson et al., 1997:569). 6 The UK media analysis consisted of two-steps. First, 475 text units were analysed from eight main British newspapers2 published in the 2010-2014 period. The text units were selected from the lexis-nexis database by entering food security or food poverty as key words which resulted in a total of 2572 articles. The text units were selected according to their relevance, source, topic and number of articles in that source. Following Candel et al., (2014), an inductive frame analysis was applied using the qualitative software NVIVO to code problem definitions, proposed solutions and moral bases displayed in the different newspaper articles. The eleven resulting frames were discussed through semi- structured phone interviews with six experts representing non-governmental organisations and institutions working on sustainable development/sustainable food, trade unions, anti-poverty campaigners, academics and agricultural experts. These interviews were instrumental in the establishment of connections among frames and in the discussion of their relevance in public and political debates. Section three discusses these eleven food security framings constructed in the UK media with the objective of gaining an in-depth understanding of narrative formation and its policy implications. Section four presents the second analytical phase, where these eleven frames are further examined under the justice framework proposed to understand how food security debates operationalise different definitions of justice. Using justice as a bridging concept, section five discusses the emergence of two main justice narratives in UK popular debates and their (dis)connections with the justice literature. Finally, section six outlines the conclusions of the paper highlighting how superficial approaches to justice can hinder the delivery of good food for all. 2 . A n a n a l y t i c a l f r a m e w o r k t o p r o b l e m a t i s e j u s t i c e n a r r a t i v e s Food security is widely acknowledged as a situation that exists when all people, at all times, have physical, social and economic access to sufficient, safe and nutritious food that meets their dietary needs and food preferences for an active and healthy life (FAO, 2002). This definition appeals to basic notions of equality. In fact, food security is increasingly associated with notions of sustainability and justice, acknowledging that 2 The newspapers selected were the Guardian, Telegraph, The Sun, The observer, The Independent, The evening standard, Daily Mail and The Mirror. 7 food systems that are environmentally sound but socially unacceptable would not be resilient in the future and vice versa (Garnett and Godfray, 2012; Sonnino et al., 2014). In this regard, by and large, social movements, policy makers and academics resort to social justice as a way of qualifying food security. For example, Kirwan and Maye (2013) call for an official UK interpretation of food security that better accommodates social justice imperatives p. , while others identify specific social justice issues such as farmworker rights, economic concentration and hunger (Clancy, 1994). However, even when considering the different narratives under the food security consensus frame, there are difficulties to explicitly define justice, treating the term as a broadly shared antidote to distinct inequalities (based on race, class, gender, etc.) and generally promoting progressive rather than radical change (see for example Alkon, 2014; Holt Gimenez and Shattuck, 2011). In the study of the intersections between food security and justice the concept of food justice holds particular interest. This concept emerges out of diverse social and environmental justice concerns to highlight distinct socio-economic, racial and cultural inequalities within the food system. Food justice is intimately associated with a section of the US food movement that aims to combat causes, processes and outcomes that create food inequalities (Agyeman and McEntee, 2014), ensuring that the benefits and risks of where, what, and how food is grown and produced, transported and distributed, and accessed and eaten are shared fairly (Gottlieb and Joshi, 2010:6). Nevertheless, different voices raise concerns over the multiple meanings and interpretations of food justice (Gottlieb and Joshi, 2010; Sbicca, 2012), as well as its focus on consumption, access, race and class; generally privileging the local and micro-scale practices ahead of a more comprehensive and multilevel account of the food system (Cadieux and Slocum, 2015; Jarosz, 2014). As Cadieux and Slocum (2015:15) put it if food justice means anything, it may stand for nothing—or, worse, serve to undermine the credibility and rigor of substantive food justice practices . Accordingly, they call for more clarity around what it means to create socially just food systems including a more rigorous food justice scholarship and activism that discloses how increasing food justice claims actually further justice. In order to do so, there is a need to reconnect food justice and other food claims food security, food sovereignty, the right to food, food democracy, etc. see Sonnino et al., 8 (2016) for a recent review) with the vast literature that problematises the concept of justice more generally. In this section I outline debates and key contributions on justice from political philosophy, social science and geographical literature. This allows us to identify different dimensions of justice which are instrumental to broadening narrow definitions that have prevailed in food debates (Loo, 2014). 2.1 From distributive justice to productive justice Political scientist John Rawls (1971) reinvigorated the debate on social justice in the 1970s, defining social justice as fairness. Stemming from this definition, he proposed a way to design a system of justice, invoking the notion of a veil of ignorance on the initial endowments of different people, to ensure that the distribution of goods and bads is as equitable as possible. This fair equality of opportunity principle is complemented by a difference principle that only permits inequalities that work to the advantage of the worst-off. Equality is then the logical definition of justice as well as the guiding principle for an appropriate system of justice. This idea of distributive justice, that is, of justice as distributing the goods and bads that we have been assigned arbitrary at birth, has received criticisms from different fronts. First, Marxist or radical critics posit questions around the object of justice, that is, what needs to be equalised (i.e. outcomes or opportunities), and how to deal with spatial, temporal and social unevenness in the process of defining equal goods and bads. In this context, Harvey (1992) calls for the application of historical-geographical materialist methods to understand the production of power differentials that result in distinct conceptions of justice mobilised by diverse groups in the struggle for ideological hegemony. Consequently, considering justice as a universal principle is problematic since there are competing interpretations of good and bad that need to be acknowledged. In this line, the prominent political philosopher Iris Marion Young (1990) developed an early post-structural critique highlighting the politics of difference at play and stressing the difficulties associated with constructing a theory of justice to become a universal standard for evaluating institutions and relations. Young (1990) defines justice as the elimination or reduction of oppression, which has five faces – exploitation, marginalisation, powerlessness, cultural imperialism and violence. Finally, and likened to 9 the development of the capabilities approach (see Nussbaum, 2003), Sen (2009) recently formulated a theory of justice that aims to clarify how we can proceed to address questions of enhancing justice and removing injustice, rather than to offer resolutions of questions about the nature of perfect justice p. ix . His proposal is to build a comparative approach that allows us to assess the justice of a situation or process by reference to other situations without having a perfect theory. Taken together, these criticisms led to a formulation of productive or participative justice approaches that highlight not only the redistribution of material resources, but also the need to recognise different realities and allow them to participate in the development of institutions O Connor, 98). In this line, Fraser (2008) defines justice as parity of participation, identifying economic, cultural and political obstacles that prevent people from participating as full partners in social interaction. 2.2 A framework to unpack justice narratives The analysis of different conceptualisations of justice prompts us to identify two main challenges in defining justice: what counts as a matter of justice and who counts as a subject of justice. These challenges are examined below, and constitute a framework to analyse how justice narratives are constructed. 2.2.1 The what of justice Fraser (2008) proposes three dimensions to address what counts as a matter of justice. These three dimensions are directly linked to the evolution of theoretical approaches to justice as succinctly summarised above, but also highlight key elements at play when constructing a justice narrative. The first dimension relates to the economic elements of justice, where distributive justice scholars have made an important contribution. Debates around the economic dimension of justice include supporters of equalising outcomes but also scholars that emphasise the importance of applying justice parameters to redistribute opportunities (Waterstones, 2009). The second dimension relates to cultural aspects of justice, championed by post- structuralist critics who argue for the recognition of difference in front of universalising and sometimes blanket approaches in defining equality and fairness. Young (1990) addresses the importance of difference and identifies cultural imperialism as an essential 10 face of oppression, that is, how dominant groups construct a social hierarchy of difference by portraying their experiences and cultural products as superior. This hierarchy creates moral norms that condition the identification of injustices. Nevertheless, Smith (2000) points out that recent preoccupation with difference can ultimately be divisive, with the risk of eroding the sense of human sameness or close similarity to ground a broader egalitarian project (p.1151). Smith draws on the foundations of human sameness - including aspects of care and human needs – to call for a wider recognition of sameness in justice evaluations without abandoning the awareness of the particularity of persons and places brought by post-structuralist contributions. Finally, there is also a political dimension when defining the matter of justice. Early conceptualisations of distributive justice revolve around the application of justice principles. (owever, as O Connor (1998) points out, any definition of justice striving for equality should include the process of production of justice. This participatory or productive approach to social justice aims to include the potential for people to participate fully in the conditions, situations and decision that give rise to particularly distributions of goods and bads in the first place. For example, environmental justice claims are not only about redistributions of goods and bads, but also about whose values and visions of the environment are recognised as well as who participates in decision- making and deliberation spaces (Martinez-Alier, 2014; Moragues-Faus and Morgan, 2015; Sikor and Newell, 2014). One of the main characteristics of political injustice is, therefore, misrepresentation, where miss-framing – or when questions of justice are wrongly framed in a way that exclude some from consideration Faser, : - constitutes a key mechanism to create injustice. This miss-framing not only applies to what counts as a matter of justice but also who counts as a subject of justice, which includes defining who is affected by given structures and therefore holds a moral standing as a subject of justice in relation to it (see Barnett, 2012). 2.2.2 The who of justice The second key challenge in defining justice approaches revolves around determining who counts as a subject of justice, which includes clarifying the sites and the scales of justice. When demarcating the sites of justice, Barnett (2011) identifies two main focuses 11 in current moral and philosophical debates, either emphasising the coercive institutions of the basic structure or the non-coercive fields of personal conduct and ethos. In the first group, Rawls (1999) argues that the subject of justice should be the institutions of society which sustain inequalities - what he called the basic structure of society - while individual choices and attitudes should not be subject to the principles of justice. On the contrary, Cohen (2009) supports the inclusion of non-coercive structures - such as conventions, social ethos and personal choices - in the evaluation of justice. Young (2011) breaks this polarised debate to call for a more complex analysis of injustice that posits the individual as the central locus of ethical responsibility but also recognises the central role of structures in producing injustices. She calls for a shared responsibility, a model in which responsibility is distributed across complex networks of causality and agency (Barnett, 2011; Young, 2007). According to this model, being responsible means that one has an obligation to join with others in order to transform the structural processes to make their outcomes just (Young, 2011:96). Defining the sites subject to justice is closely related to problematising the scales or the scopes of justice. The scales of obligations of justice are widely considered to be defined by membership to a particular political community, mainly the nation-state (Miller, 2008; Rawls, 1971). This Rawlsian position basically holds that obligations of justice with other human beings presuppose the existence of shared political institutions Young, 2011:136), and therefore global distributive justice could only rely on the possibility of a global basic structure (Buchanan, 2003; Pogge, 2002; see Barnett, 2011 for a debate on the existence of a global institutional order). However, critics of this position highlight the arbitrary membership to a nation-state from a moral point of view, stressing the role of power in the evolution of political communities and boundaries (Young, 2011). Furthermore, relationships between people can be unjust without political institutions that govern them and, at the same time, non-governmental collective actors can have an important role in the creation of injustices. Indeed, current globalising processes – including discourses of justice and corresponding institutional arrangements but also capitalist developments (Fraser, 2008; Sikor and Newell, 2014) –have reshaped existing forms of inequality and modified the spaces available for the pursuit of justice beyond Westphalian states (Newell, 2012). 12 In contrast, other authors support a cosmopolitan-utilitarian view where moral agents have obligations to all human and even non-human beings (Singer, 1993; Unger, 1996). This stance also receives criticism for being overly individualistic, disregarding the roles of institutions and collective action as well as failing to propose specific actions. In the face of these two conceptions, Young (2011) argues for a shared responsibility of all agents contributing to structural processes involved in reproducing injustice. Those processes cut across jurisdictional boundaries creating moral geographies as illustrated by the environmental justice scholarship that demonstrates how place-specific policies and practices can have consequences that cross national boundaries, affect multiple scales, and extend across global networks (Holifield et al., 2009: 595). This review of justice conceptualisations allows the construction of an analytical framework to examine justice narratives. Table 1 summarises the dimensions involved in developing these narratives, as well as key questions and debates on the who and what of justice. This analytical framework constitutes a tool to navigate conflicting views, establish new connections among narratives and support the development of more complex accounts of justice in different food security approaches as discussed below. 13 Table 1. Summary of the analytical framework to identify key justice challenges and its constitutive dimensions Challenges Dimensions Key questions and debates The what of justice Economic: Redistribution Do narratives champion equalisation of outcomes (final goods enjoyed) and/or equalisation of opportunities (possibilities of access)? Social and cultural: Recognition Do narratives emphasise sameness of all humans and/or they call for recognition of difference (e.g. vulnerable groups)? Political: Representation Do narratives consider the application of justice principles (by who, to who) and/or do they problematise the process of producing justice (who participates in defining justice)? The who of justice Scales of justice Do narratives refer to national boundaries (linked to the capacity of the national state to act, e.g. legislate) and/or do they include global perspectives (other geographies are implicated in defining and applying justice principles)? Sites of justice Do narratives consider the structures of the basic society as the places to apply justice principles and/or they focus on individuals when evaluating justice? Source: Author s own elaboration 3. UK media food security framings: a segmented discursive foodscape The UK is a particularly interesting example to study food security frames given its combination of increasing dependency on food imports since the 1980s - which today constitute 40% of all food consumed in the UK (DEFRA, 2014a) – as well as rising numbers of people experiencing diet-related diseases and food poverty. In England, 64% of the population is overweight, with low-income families being particularly affected (HSE, 2013). Unsurprisingly, one of the main concerns now for the UK s population is food prices, which have increased by 18% in real terms between 2007 and 2012, affecting mainly low-income households (DEFRA, 2014b). Government figures estimate that there are around 13 million people in poverty in the UK, that is, one in five people (Department for Work and Pensions, 2014). Alternative sources state that four million people suffer from food poverty (Gordon et al., 2000) and that around three million people suffer from undernourishment or are at risk of being underfed (Brotherton et al., 2010). There has been an expansion of charity-run food banks around the UK, with estimates of around 500,000 residents are now reliant on food aid; and the Trussell Trust food banks have 14 delivered 3 days emergency food to 913,138 people in 2013/2014 (Lambie-Mumford et al.,2014). The media has been active in reporting some of these trends, and particularly the food banks surge (Wells and Caraher, 2014). The analysis of the UK media framing process from 2010 until 2014 resulted in the identification and characterisation eleven food security frames. Following the methodology of Candel et al. (2014), the table below summarises these frames, including the way in which each frame defines food insecurity as a problem and identifies related threats, key concepts and associated solutions suggested with examples of specific policies, and the moral bases mobilised. 15 Table 2 Food security (FS) frames emerging from UK media analysis Frames Problems definition/threats Key concepts / suggested solutions Policies Moral bases Distributive justice Increasing social inequalities, Violence and riots, Economic crisis, Cuts to public expenditure, Tax avoidance. People are arbitrarily born with distinct endowments. This is unfair and needs to be corrected in order to deliver FS for all. Redistribution and effective welfare enable FS. Increase minimum wage/living wages. Reform welfare state. We are arbitrarily endowed with different resources and skills. These should be redistributed fairly. Social justice as fairness and equality. Ecological Soil fertility loss, Pollution, Climate change, Pressures on biodiversity. Sustainable food production. Organic and environmentally friendly production practices. Animal Welfare. Inter-generational sustainability, Respect for nature, Eco-centrism. Food safety Spread of animal & plant diseases, Food chain complexity & inefficiencies, Food contamination, Cuts on public expenditure. Food safety standards are key for national FS. Increase controls of food safety. Scientific evidence, Hygenic-sanitary measures to ensure public health. Free trade Dependency on food imports and international trade, Price volatility and surge, Food chain complexity & inefficiencies, Spread of animal & plant diseases, Food contamination. Relying on competitive advantage theories and creating global food chains is the way to assure an efficient and affordable food provision for all. Liberalise trade. Freedom of choice, Efficiency. Individualistic Economic crisis, Short term crisis, Welfare dependency. People are responsible for their own choices and associated consequences, therefore they are the ones responsible for assuring FS in their households. Reduce welfare state, Achieve high levels of employment. Individual freedom and responsibility. Productionist Climate change and bad weather, Spread of animal & plant diseases, Population growth, Violence and riots, Anti-GM lobby. Stimulating production and increasing productivity. Invest in sustainable intensification techniques. Invest in technologies to increasing yields. Every country should be involved in producing more food and increase yields, using technological advances. Quality Unsustainable purchasing & eating practices, Increasing social inequalities, Economic crisis, Prices. Having access to nutritious, healthy and good food. Promotion of local foods. Promotion of east well guides, eat five a day. Nutritious food as a right for everybody. Promoting local/national and 16 indigenous food as part of the rural landscape, preserving identity. Regulatory Dependency on food imports and international trade, Price volatility and surge, Food chain complexity & inefficiencies, Unsustainable purchasing & eating practices, Food fraud and crime, Increasing social inequalities, Food industry lobbying & advertisement, Tax avoidance. Markets work inefficiently since they do not consider environmental, social and economic externalities or the fulfilment of the right to food. Governments are responsible for people s FS. Protectionist measures. Grants and payments to protect and support national markets and producers. Sugar and unhealthy food taxes. Regulate advertisement. State as steward of its citizens, responsible for delivering rights. Solidarity3 Increasing social inequalities, Population growth, Price surges, Economic crisis. People should help each other to achieve FS, building a Big society . Food assistance is an expression of this community and solidarity spirit delivering short-term and effective solutions for people in need. Empower communities, devolve resources. Human solidarity, community spirit, compassion. Sovereignty Increasing social inequalities, Food industry lobbying & advertisement, Dependency on food imports and international trade, Economic crisis, Land competition, Food chain complexity & inefficiencies, Financial speculation, Cuts in public expenditure, GMs. People and communities must have control over their food systems in order to deliver FS. Provide rights to people (access to land, water, seeds etc.). Protect local economies through trade barriers. Right to decide on the food system, tackle power imbalances. Technology Low farming productivity, Soil fertility loss, Population growth, Climate change and bad weather, Anti-GM lobby. New technological developments would deliver FS for all. Invest and deregulate the development of new technologies. Scientific evidence, Efficiency, Freedom of choice. 3 This fra e is a ed solidarity i order to refle t the des riptors used i the edia arti les a alysed. Ho e er, this defi itio of solidarity represe ts only one of the manifold meanings and practices of solidarity linked to food insecurity or food poverty dynamics. For example other radical approaches to solidarity or community building rooted in anarchist principles such are food not bombs (see Heynen (2010) are by and large absent in print media outlets. 17 According to experts interviewed, these frames capture the areas where conversation and controversies hinge in the UK food security debate. These frames show the complexity of food security narratives and the current segmentation of food debates that, among other limitations, preclude holistic accounts of food security challenges. This lack of holistic understanding is clearly exemplified by the suggested solutions presented by these narratives which tend to deal with specific aspects such as food safety, boosting production or improving welfare assistance. However, there are clear correlations among the different frames, many of them sharing the identification of key problems and in some cases elements of the moral basis. Indeed, when presented with these frames several respondents identified two main sets of frames that impinge on national policy debates reproducing the polarised positions outlined in the literature (see above). On the one hand the productionist, free trade and technology frames were acknowledged as the main drivers of national policy (and also European policy) which one expert described as a consistent policy position with regard to food production, food systems and the food economy . On the other hand, a second set of frames is made up of ecological, regulatory and distributive justice narratives; championed by a diverse set of charities, NGOs and think tanks in the UK. Experts showed a range of moral and justice concerns when asked about the relevance of these frames in public debates. For example, an interviewee supporting a mixture of productionist, free trade and technology frames to address food security challenges asserted that the UK is benign when it comes to social justice. ) think there is a general socio-democratic feel about the way you look at food as sort of an essential part of life . On the contrary, another informant downplayed the role of these three frames resorting as well to justice claims and stating that the productionist and the technology narrative are quite powerful because it is quite emotive to say we can feed hungry people and we can do it now. But now is not about a fair distribution of nutrition, it is about profits. In order to understand better these linkages between food security and justice, the next section analyses in depth how different definitions of justice are mobilised in the UK media food security frames. 18 4. What do you mean by justice? This section presents the results of the analysis of the UK food security frames under the justice analytical framework proposed in section two. The main aim is to understand how food security frames converge and diverge around particular justice dimensions, and, how these distinct justice definitions underpin support for particular policy solutions. 4.1 The matter of justice: economic, socio-cultural and political dimensions of justice in UK media food security frames The individualistic and the distributive justice frame are particularly engaged with defining what is the matter of justice, while the other frames generally position themselves around specific dimensions. The individualistic frame conceptualises the matter of justice as the equalisation of opportunities that arises from freedom of choice and de-regulation. Food insecurity is, therefore, the result of making the wrong individual choices, like purchasing the wrong foods, spending money on the wrong goods (e.g. TVs) or not working hard enough (see figure 1). This narrative enhances the sameness of individuals and individual rights, claiming that we all are free to make our own decisions and (in the UK) have similar basic conditions to fulfil our needs. Cultural recognition is therefore overlooked within this frame, avoiding any reference to distinct needs and values that groups in society might hold. This sameness resonates as fairness to part of the population, although in some cases is constructed in opposition to others, such as highlighting the use of foodbanks by immigrants (see for example The unpalatable truth about food banks the left finds so hard to swallow Daily Mail 13/05/2014) or stressing the wealth of the UK in front of other countries. Therefore, the initial premise of the sameness of individuals is frequently jeopardised by constructions of us and the others , raising questions about who is deserving or entitled to share this sameness. 19 Figure 1. Headlines related to the individualistic frame The free trade frame also champions the distribution of opportunities and appeals to sameness, in this case calling for all countries to participate under equal trade conditions in the global market. Based on the comparative advantage theory proposed by David Ricardo, the definition of food security under this frame is that free flow of goods allows food to be produced at the lowest possible cost, building global food chains that assure efficient and affordable food provision for all and providing business opportunities. Similarly to the individualistic frame, this definition of justice resonates with the neo- liberal project (Ferguson, 2010), reinforcing the expression of people s freedom of choice through the market. Also, these two frames do not consider the different initial endowments of individuals or countries that might jeopardise ideals of sameness when participating for example in the so-called free markets. Contrastingly, the distributive justice frame as deployed in the media appeals to fairness and equality, calling for a redistribution of goods and bads that lead not only to better opportunities but that result in fairer outcomes. The definition of the what of justice, 20 therefore, has an important economic dimension that coalesces around policy demands to have an effective welfare system and assure living wages. In fact, much of the rhetoric around this distributive justice frame refers to austerity measures such as benefits cuts and delays as a generator of food insecurity in the UK. This position has been reinforced by investigations on food banks showing that many of their users are suffering from changes in welfare payments (Lambie-Mumford et al., 2014, Oxfam and Church Action, 2013). While this frame is sensitive to different groups and needs - showcasing a number of individual s situations such as single mothers or disabled people - it does not unpack culturally diverse definitions of what is good food for all. In common with the individualistic frame, notions of sameness are also brought to the fore, highlighting different life stories and the idea that it might happen to you see for example article Food poverty: You think it doesn t happen to normal people The Guardian 06/06/2013). Figure 2. Headlines related to the distributive justice frame4 4 The image of the front page of the Daily Mirror shows a child crying. Following UNICEF ethical guidelines, this figure does not sho the hild s fa e to a oid further stig atisatio of a i age that has e o e i o i i the UK food poverty debate. 21 The analysis of the media food security frames under the justice framework reveals that practically none of them referred to the political dimension of justice or acknowledged (mis)representation mechanisms. Even in the distributive justice frame, there is an absence of contestation or reflection regarding how people suffering from food poverty are represented in this narrative, using (strategically) the rise of food bank users as a means to gather support for specific policies such as benefit reforms or living wage campaigns. Moreover, the participation of food insecure people in producing - and not only benefiting from - a more just system is seldom discussed. The only frame explicitly tackling issues of empowerment and participation is the sovereignty frame which argues for people and communities to regain control over their food systems in order to deliver food security. However, in the UK context food sovereignty is rarely discussed in the media apart from international events related to La Via Campesina and as an umbrella term to amalgamate a myriad of food initiatives. The diverse strands of independent, sustainable and organic food producers are, at present, little more than a glimmer of light in the gloom, but they may represent the beginnings of a movement for food sovereignty, restoring the connection between the people of this country and more democratic ownership of the chain that brings food from the fields to our kitchens (The Guardian, 26/03/2014) The food sovereignty frame relies on the right to decide over how food is produced and accessed. This clearly aims to tackle power imbalances as a precondition to delivering sustainability, justice, and ultimately food security for all. However, there are conceptual and practical gaps in linking these global goals to the needs of people actually suffering from food insecurity within the UK. Other frames do not engage directly in participation issues but draw attention to key aspects of the political process of defining justice. For example, the ecological frame highlights intergenerational aspects of sustainability and therefore the need to establish a temporal dimension in the formulation of policy solutions. In the case of the technological and safety frames, they make explicit references to application mechanisms of justice; specifically, they share a strong focus on scientific evidence as the basis to guide decision making. 22 The Government has a position on GM foods which is, provided that it's used safely and responsibly, it can deliver benefits and help address the challenge of global food security. We have to ensure public safety and take decisions based on the scientific evidence (Daily Mail, 11/12/2012). The technological frame deploys a particular definition of scientific evidence, including only experts and mostly natural science findings. Science is therefore seen as an objective and impartial tool to guide policy, and opponents to developments such as bio-technology are seen as having a lack of scientific understanding. This frame rarely includes as scientific evidence studies that highlight socio-cultural impacts of technology or the development of low-cost techniques and knowledge. Nevertheless, the safety frame includes reports and inquiries that rely on socio-economic data as scientific evidence and also highlights the importance of public perception in policy making processes (see for example Elliot (2014) on the horse meat scandal). 4.2 The who of justice: sites and scales of justice in food security frames The food security frames identified in the UK media engage more actively in constructing different sites and scales of justice than in defining the matter of justice. The analysis reveals a polarised position between whether the sites subject to justice are individual behaviours or the institutions of the basic structure and consequently support very distinct policy interventions. In the first case, the individualistic frame portrays food security as an individual matter, the site of justice or who is responsible are individuals instead of institutions. People s attitudes and practices are therefore key to being food secure, and independent from public policies or market forces, mainly understood as people making the wrong choices . (Edwina Currie) declared that food poverty simply did not exist. "It's about choices", she said. What she meant was that she believed poor people had enough money, they just spent it on fags and booze and getting into debt with loan sharks. (The Guardian 03/03/2014). In the UK, this frame has actively been deployed throughout the food banks debate contesting the reach or even existence of food poverty in the country. In this context, some commentators have argued that some people are taking advantage of the welfare system and charity initiatives and call for subsequent policy reform. 23 Some people like to believe that there has been this enormous upsurge in food poverty. My point is that there have always been poor people in this country. … The fact is that food banks are a new phenomenon. … )f you provide a service, people use it Daily Mail 13/03/2014). In a more nuanced position, the solidarity frame as deployed in the media avoids pointing out specific sites of justice, trying to de-politicise food security solutions through an appeal to build strong, active and self-reliant communities. In this line, these communities would not expect support from the state, what makes this discourse of building a Big Society 5 compatible with elements of the individualistic frame that locate individual freedom and responsibility at its heart. Similarly, these ideas of individual freedom and responsibility resonate with the technological and free-trade frame. These last two emphasise individual freedom particularly in relation to consumer and producer choice that is, by and large, materialised through access to global food chains. Nevertheless, these frames recognise the role of the state in delivering reforms that would progress in solving food insecurity by reinforcing free competition or the introduction of specific technologies. The Government sometimes says it can t do anything about the rise in food prices, but there are policies that can be adopted. On commodity prices, we need to double our efforts to support free-trade agreements in agricultural goods, support global adoption of high-yield crops and put food production at the heart of our development programmes abroad. (The Telegraph 19/06/2014) The Environment, Food and Rural Affairs select committee urged ministers to do more to bring in GM food and to get the EU to loosen curbs on the controversial crops to boost "food security" (The Mirror 01/07/2014) On a different note, the regulatory frame emphasises the responsibility of the national state to deliver food security for all, deeming markets as inefficient tools that ignore 5 The idea of the Big society in the UK is by and large mostly associated with the conservative agenda which aims to integrate a free market approach with a theory of social solidarity based on voluntarism (Alcock et al., 2012). This concept commends that a significant amount of responsibility for the running of a society is devolved to local communities and volunteers. 24 environmental, social and economic costs or the need to fulfil human rights, as illustrated below. Finally, there is an answer that lies in treating food security as a priority, rather than as a soft commodity to be traded like any other. Its production and trading should be much more heavily regulated, and protected (The Guardian 01/06/2011). (Tory MP) Laura Sandys called for ministers to take a stronger regulatory approach to tackle rampant food inflation, to prevent consumers being ripped off, and to rebuild the UK's consumer's declining food skills. That meant controlling food policy she said, rather than delegating it to the supermarkets (The Guardian 04/06/2013). The safety frame is also related to the regulatory frame, considering necessary the state intervention to regulate specific areas such as developing hygienic bureaucratic norms to assure minimum standards. Nevertheless, food frauds and scares have brought to the fore contrasting positions on responsibility, that is, whether food safety should be more regulated and monitored by public agencies or be devolved to the private sector. The distributive justice frame clearly posits socio-economic structures as the main root cause of food insecurity in the UK, and therefore also proposes that the principles of justice should be applied to institutions - which play a key role in solving unjust situations such as food insecurity. Indeed, this frame advocates for an improved welfare system and other forms of state intervention including raising minimum wages. Trussell Trust's chairman, said: )n the last year we've seen things get worse, rather than better, for many people on low incomes.' In a highly political intervention, he also called for the Government to drop sanctions against benefit claimants and increase the minimum wage (Daily Mail 17/04/2014). The polarised positions around individuals or structures as legitimate sites of justice permeate the definition of the scales of justice where the analysis reveals three main levels: global, national and local (including communities). By and large, the frames championing the institutions of the basic structure as a site of justice resort to the national level. For example, in the case of distributive justice the institutions pointed out as key for solving food insecurity are located at the national level and mostly relate to the UK s socio-economic policies. In this regard, global discourses around food security for all are rarely included in media articles tackling food poverty in the UK and therefore 25 restrict their definition of the who of justice to national boundaries. This particularly contrasts with debates and proposals of environmental justice which impinge upon global rights, and reinforces the idea that food justice claims tend to remain local and potentially exclusionary. The regulatory and safety frame also refers mostly to UK s responsibilities towards its citizens. Interestingly, the individualistic frame champions individual responsibility mostly in relation to the UK context but also in some cases this narrative is applied to justify why other countries are food insecure (e.g. due to corruption, mismanagement or lack of knowledge). While the individualistic frame is very much constructed around the UK and its particular dynamics, it does not necessarily stress the nation as the scale where justice principles and norms are implemented. However, as stated above, it does mobilise nationality and national borders to construct a compelling narrative. The productionist and the technology frame reinforce this global scale of justice, asserting that by increasing food production and developing technologies to increase yields in the UK and abroad, they are contributing to global food security. Children are going blind in impoverished parts of the world because of the "hang-up" of opponents of GM foods, Environment Secretary Owen Paterson warned today (The Evening Standard, 14/10/2013). At the other end of the spectrum, the quality frame celebrates - among other attributes - local food or British food, putting emphasis on high-quality products, grow-your-own or initiatives such as farmers markets. Some commentators argue that this construction of quality is linked to middle-class concerns that create exclusive spaces where these types of food can be accessed (see for example Guthman, 2008). In this frame, local/national and indigenous foods are presented as part of the British identity. Nevertheless, uncritical approaches to local food have been reported as detrimental in terms of advancing towards equality, since they might reproduce power relations and also develop narratives only accessible to certain societal groups with specific cultural and economic endowments (Johnston, 2008; Moragues-Faus, 2016). This potential local trap permeates the construction of justice developed by the solidarity frame where solutions to food insecurity revolve around the devolution of powers to communities and the 26 promotion of solidarity spirit by encouraging people to take an active role in their local environment. In Oxford, a food bank was started up four and a half years ago, based on a sustainable model. … As an example of the much-disparaged Big Society , it could hardly be bettered. The volunteers – who … come from every background and represent every political hue – have co-operated to build an organisation with local roots, serving local needs, without any subsidy from state sources whatsoever. (The Telegraph 19/06/2014). This local focus might potentially obscure the distinct capacity of communities to self- organise and tackle food insecurity. Indeed, having time to engage in alternative practices or voluntary activities often requires a pre-existing class privilege (Gross, 2009). Furthermore, this local community focus can reinforce negative unintended consequences of particular food practices on distant communities given the globalised character of existing food chains. Recent literature on food banks has been active in highlighting how food assistance programmes can indeed reproduce root causes of food insecurity and domination relations (see for example (Minkoff-Zern, 2014)). 27 Table 3. Analysis of food security frames under justice framework Challenges The what of justice The who of justice Dimensions Frames Economic: Redistribution Social and cultural: Recognition Political: Representation Scales of justice Sites of justice Distributive justice Outcomes and opportunities to be food secure Difference (vulnerable groups but not diverse definitions of good food), sameness (it can happen to you) Application National Structure Ecological Outcomes around environmental protection - *Future generations Global - Food Safety Outcomes to be food secure - *Scientific evidence National Structure Free trade Opportunities (countries) Sameness (trade agreements, free competition) Application Global Individual Individualistic Opportunities to access food Sameness but disregard of certain groups as less deserving Application National/global Individual Productionist - - - Global - Quality - - - Local - Regulatory - - - National Structure Solidarity Opportunities - - Local Not structures Sovereignty Opportunities (access to food but also rights) and outcomes - Production of justice Global/local Structures Technology - - *Scientific evidence Global Individual 28 5. Neoliberal and structural justice narratives in food security debates The analysis of media food security frames under the justice framework allows identifying new linkages and gaps that result in the characterisation of two main justice narratives. Firstly, the free trade, individualistic and technology frames share a neoliberal justice narrative revolving around providing equal opportunities, championing application of principles and identifying individual practices as key sites of justice. The scale of this neoliberal narrative is rather fluid, with a strong global focus but favouring the interests and needs of a particular nation and its citizens. The term neoliberal justice has been used in the literature to emphasise a formulation of justice that reduces the explanations of social and political theory to the behaviour of individual actors rather than structures of society (Okereke, 2007), as well highlighting its connection to the neoliberal project based on liberating individual entrepreneurial freedoms within an institutional framework characterised by strong private property rights, free markets, and free trade (Harvey, 2005:2). However, the neoliberal justice narrative in food security public debate combines this policy framework with ideas of sameness and equal opportunities to access markets or jobs. Secondly, the distributive justice, food safety and regulatory frames construct a structural justice narrative that not only focuses on opportunities but is largely occupied with the actual outcomes and the application of justice principles. These principles are applied to the institutions of the basic structure primarily located at the national level. The term structural injustice has been used to reject individualising and blaming justice perspectives. According to Young (2006) structural injustice exists when social processes put large categories of persons under a systematic threat of domination or deprivation of the means to develop and exercise their capacities, at the same time as these processes enable others to dominate or have a wide range of opportunities for developing and exercising their capacities (p.114). Nevertheless, and contrarily to the narrow structural justice narrative used in food security debates, Young argues that individuals bear responsibility for structural injustice because they contribute by their actions to the processes that produce unjust outcome (p.119). Consequently, the structural processes can be altered only if many actors in diverse social positions work together to intervene in these processes to produce different outcomes p. . However, the structural justice narrative identified throughout the media analysis falls into a rather narrow conceptualisation of structure that hinders the development of a 29 range of state and non-state led actions to correct current food insecurity dynamics. That is, to propose solutions that go beyond welfare reforms and minimum salaries. Finally, the rest of the food security frames do not articulate a comprehensive justice narrative. However, they bring to the fore specific aspects of justice such the importance of considering the temporal aspects in the definition of justice (ecological frame), the role of communities and local spaces (solidarity frame) or the importance of questioning how justice is produced (sovereignty frame). In general, the UK media food security frames show a rather narrow definition of justice in relation to the existing justice literature and its development since the 70s - when liberal definitions of justice started to be contested. Nevertheless, the results of the analysis show that justice claims are central in building an appealing food security frame. The structural justice narrative constitutes a clear example of this lack of definition and evidences the need to further qualify justice assertions by its proponents - particularly since, according to interviewees, the media frames capture the wider UK food security debate. This narrative aims to bring to the fore social justice goals in the convoluted UK media, however, it fails to articulate a comprehensive account of cultural recognition, over-relying on food banks as a key framing device of food insecurity. This results in a definition of vulnerable groups in relation to food bank users (a characteristic shared by other frames) which highlights specific food practices (mainly at the consumption end) and obscures other roles that as citizens all of us might perform. This focus also excludes different lived experiences of food poverty that do not necessarily include using food banks; as well as different accounts of what is good food. Accordingly, this narrative overlooks the existence of vulnerable distant communities and how proposed policies might contribute to reproduce or mitigate global inequalities. A more systemic account of food security, often absent in food poverty debates, will allow the uncovering of the existing linkages with global processes implicated in current and future food insecurity outcomes such as climate change or food production. As illustrated above, the sole focus on the institutions of the basic structure as the sites of justice precludes establishing these multi-level linkages that acknowledge a contingent geography of injustice. This justice narrative could benefit from engaging with shared responsibility conceptualisations of justice when identifying who is the subject of justice, and therefore its policy targets. Finally, this frame also disregards the importance of participation when addressing 30 inequality which constitutes a key mechanism to redress structural and root causes of injustice (see Fraser, 2009). 6. Conclusions: reclaiming justice to deliver food security for all This paper contributes to the current food security agenda by exploring the connections and disconnections of public food security narratives and their relationality through the concept of justice. In order to broaden and deepen the linkages between food security and justice literature, and practice, two key justice challenges (the what and the who of justice) are expounded to build an innovative analytical framework. The application of this innovative justice framework to the analysis of the UK media food security debate has revealed gaps and ways forward for food security practitioners and the associated scholarship. First, the identification and characterisation of eleven food security frames reveal clear disconnections and partial accounts of the systemic nature of food insecurity, including the proposal of disparate solutions and policies (see table 2). These marked contrasts limit the adoption of integral approaches and innovative practices that have proved instrumental in delivering good food for all- as the literature shows elsewhere (see for example Brunori et al., 2013). Secondly, the media frames engage recurrently with different notions of justice, revealing the contingent relationship between food security and justice claims. Furthermore, the concept of justice constitutes a bridging device across narratives that has uncovered different controversies and relations than those recurrently portrayed in academic and policy debates. Results of the analysis show a clear polarisation with respect to the economic dimension of justice (with frames championing opportunities vs those focused on outcomes), the cultural dimension (where sameness and recognition of difference are seldom articulated) and the site of justice (whether the application of justice should pivot around individuals or the institutions of the basic structure). These distinct justice definitions have clear policy implications since they support different types of policies, for example by setting targets regarding access to food vs resulting levels of malnutrition (opportunities/outcomes), developing universal policies or working with differentiated groups (sameness/difference), and reinforcing state regulation or reducing public intervention (structure/individual). The UK media frames also showcase a very limited reflection of 31 the spatial interdependencies implicated in the food system and their role in achieving global food security outcomes, mostly limiting policies or actors interventions to the national interest. Despite the centrality of justice in popular perceptions of food security in the UK, the analysis reveals a partial engagement with justice definitions and a general overlooking of the political dimension of justice – linked to (mis)representation and participation. Yet, explicit problematisation of who participates in decision-making process and whose rights and values are recognised has proven to be essential in resolving entrenched inequalities (see Martinez-Alier, 2014). This lack of engagement in public discourse with the ideas espoused in the participative justice literature mirrors the deficiencies of academic contributions (see Loo, 2014). Furthermore, experts interviewed acknowledged that the media frames identified captured the wider public and policy food security debate; thus signalling a generalised failure of civil society, public and private stakeholders to include the process of producing justice in current narratives and policy solutions. In this context, the justice framework proposed is instrumental to unpick further these linkages between food security and justice. This framework provides a tool to evaluate justice assertions but also prompt polarised narratives and associated stakeholders to evaluate (and further define) what type and whose justice they are championing. Specifically, this analytical tool acknowledges the role of framing as a key mechanism of generating injustice at the economic and social level (Fraser, 2008) by creating powerful discourses that outline who is subject to what justice principles and producing social realities that translate into targets for policy. This type of analytical tool contributes to the implementation of deliberative and reflexive food governance approaches based on fostering spaces for learning and adapting social solutions to collectively resolve food insecurities (Marsden, 2013). For example, using justice as a bridging concept we start to ask individualistic narratives how they address cultural diversity and different notions of good food, or how distributive justice proponents tackle the global scale to actually deliver good food for all. Similarly, this framework brings to the forefront different questions to elucidate in food policy arenas such as where is the site of responsibility or who is deserving to be considered in food security interventions. Ultimately, linking food security narratives to the justice framework can help to develop integrative and 32 participative policies that cut across scales, sites and dimensions of justice in order to deliver good food for all. Consequently, this framework aims not only to guide critique but also to support the creation of counter and equally compelling narratives which can begin to reconstruct a more democratic and inclusive food politics (Moragues-Faus, 2016). This paper proposes to use justice as a common thread to hold new discussions and connect food policy arenas to other spaces tackling socio-economic, cultural and political inequalities. Furthermore, and building on Young s and Fraser s work, ) contend that a food security approach that aims to provide consistently good food for all needs to incorporate a definition of justice that i) provides opportunities to access good food with a strong emphasis on final outcomes, ii) appeals to the equal rights of all peoples to food but also acknowledges different needs and definitions of good; and iii) includes the potential for people to participate fully in the conditions, situations and decisions that give rise to particular distributions of goods and bads in the first place. Recognising and unpacking the political elements of justice that are clearly manifested through representation and misrepresentation processes are key to advancing in the current conceptualisations and practices of participative food justices. Truly participative food justices necessarily depart from the acknowledgment of the global processes that connect individuals and institutions across different geographies. Indeed, multi-scalar approaches to food security and justice are essential to grasp contemporary fluid liaisons between place and power (Bauman, 2013; Conversi, 2016) which are currently fostering the emergence of multilevel, cross-sectorial and multi-site networks that do not conform to administrative boundaries, ranging from transnational corporations to sustainable food cities networks or global justice movements. This multi- scalar approach provides the grounds to dissolve individual-structure dichotomies and build shared responsibilities to deliver global and participative food justices. References Agyeman, J., McEntee, J., 2014. Moving the Field of Food Justice Forward Through the Lens of Urban Political Ecology. Geogr. Compass 8, 211–220. 33 Alcock, P., Kendall, J., Parry, J., 2012. From the third sector to the Big Society: consensus or contention in the 2010 UK General Election? Volunt. Sect. Rev. 3, 347–363. Alkon, A., 2014. Food Justice and the Challenge to Neoliberalism. Gastron. J. Food Cult. 14, 27–40. Barnett, C., 2012. Situating the geographies of injustice in democratic theory. Geoforum 43, 677–686. Barnett, C., 2011. Geography and ethics: Justice unbound. Prog. Hum. Geogr. 35, 246– 255. Bauman, Z., 2013. Liquid modernity. Jogn Wiley & Sons. Brotherton, A., Simmonds, N., Stroud, M., 2010. Malnutrition Matters Meeting Quality Standards in Nutritional Care [WWW Document]. Br. Assoc. Parenter. Enter. Nutr. (BAPEN ). URL http://www.bapen.org.uk/pdfs/toolkit-for-commissioners.pdf (accessed 8.19.14). Brunori, G., Malandrin, V., Rossi, A., 2013. Trade-off or convergence? The role of food security in the evolution of food discourse in Italy. J. Rural Stud. 29, 19–29. Buchanan, A., 2003. Justice, Legitimacy, and Self-Determination: Moral Foundations for International Law: Moral Foundations for International Law. Oxford University Press, Oxford. Cadieux, K., Slocum, R., 2015. What does it mean to do food justice. J. Polit. Ecol. 22, 1– 26. Candel, J.J.L., Breeman, G.E., Stiller, S.J., Termeer, C.J.A.M., 2014. Disentangling the consensus frame of food security: The case of the EU Common Agricultural Policy reform debate. Food Policy 44, 47–58. Clancy, K., 1994. Commentary social justice and sustainable agriculture: Moving beyond theory. Agric. Human Values 11, 77–83. Cohen, G., 2009. Rescuing justice and equality. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts. Conversi, D., 2016. Sovereignty in a Changing World: From Westphalia to Food Sovereignty. Globalizations 13, 484–498. DEFRA, 2014a. Basic Horticultural Statistics 2014. London. DEFRA, 2014b. Food Statistics Pocketbook 2014. Department for Work and Pensions, 2014. Households below average income (HBAI): 1994/95 to 2012/13. Elliot, C., 2014. Elliott Review into the Integrity and Assurance of Food Supply Networks . A national Food Crime Prevention Network, HM G. Entman, R., 1993. Framing: Towards clarification of a fractured paradigm. J. Commun. 43, 51–58. European Commission, 2010. The EU Role in Global Health. COM(2010)128 final. Accessed 01/03/2017 http://eur-lex.europa.eu/legal- content/en/TXT/?uri=CELEX:52010DC0128 34 FAO, 2002. The State of Food Insecurity in the World 2001. Rome. Ferguson, J., 2010. The Uses of Neoliberalism. Antipode 41, 166–184. Fraser, N., 2008. Scales of justice: Reimagining justice in a globalizing world. Polity, Cambridge. Fraser, N., . Justice interruptus: Critical reflections on the postsocialist condition. Routledge, New York. Freibauer, A., Mathijs, E., O´Brien, L., Treyer, S., 2011. Sustainable Food Consumption and Production in a Resource-Contrained World (Report), European Commission – Standing Committee on Agricultural Research (SCAR). The 3rd SCAR Foresight Exercise . Garnett, T., Godfray, C., 2012. Sustainable intensification in agriculture. Navigating a course through competing food system priorities. Godfray HCJ, Beddington JR, Crute IR, et al. (2010) Food security: the challenge of feeding 9 billion people. Science 327(5967): 812–818. Gordon, D., Levitas, R., Pantazis, C., Patsios, D., Payne, S., Townsend, P., Adelman, L., Ashworth, K., Middleton, S., Bradshaw, J., Williams, J., 2000. Poverty and social exclusion in Britain, Joseph Rowntree Foundation. Gottlieb, R., Joshi, A., 2010. Food justice. MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts. Gross, J., 2009. Capitalism and Its Discontents: Back-to-the-Lander and Freegan Foodways in Rural Oregon. Food Foodways 17, 57–79. Guthman, J., 2008. Bringing good food to others: investigating the subjects of alternative food practice. Cult. Geogr. 15, 431–447. Harvey, D., 2005. A brief history of neoliberalism. Oxford University Press, USA, Oxford. Harvey, D., 1992. Social Justice, Postmodernism and the City. Int. J. Urban Reg. Res. 16, 588–601. Herman, E.S. and Chomsky, N., 1988 Manufacturing Consent: The Political Economy of the Mass Media. Pantheon Books, USA. Heider, F., 1958. The psychology of interpersonal relations. Wiley, New York. Heynen, N., 2010. Cooking up non-violent civil-disobedient direct action for the hungry: Food Not Bombs and the resurgence of radical democracy in the US. Urban Stud. 47, 1225–1240. Holt Gimenez, E., Shattuck, A., 2011. Food crises, food regimes and food movements: rumblings of reform or tides of transformation? J. Peasant Stud. 38, 109–144. (opma J and Woods M Political Geographies of Food Security and Food Sovereignty . Geography Compass 8(11): 773–784. HSE, 2013. Health Survey for England - 2012. (mr) Web Master, United Kingdom. Iyengar, S., 1994. Is Anyone Responsible?: How Television Frames Political Issues. University of Chicago Press, Chicago and London. Jarosz, L., 2014. Comparing food security and food sovereignty discourses. Dialogues 35 Hum. Geogr. 4, 168–181. Johnston, J., 2008. The citizen-consumer hybrid: ideological tensions and the case of Whole Foods Market. Theory Soc. 37, 229–270. doi:10.1007/s11186-007-9058-5 Kirwan, J., Maye, D., 2013. Food security framings within the UK and the integration of local food systems. J. Rural Stud. 29, 91–100. Kneafsey, M., Dowler, E., Lambie-Mumford, H., Inman, A., Collier, R., 2013. Consumers and food security: Uncertain or empowered? J. Rural Stud. 29, 101–112. Lambie-Mumford, H.., Crossley, D., Jensen, E., Verbeke, M., Dowler, E., 2014. Household Food Security in the UK: A Review of Food Aid [WWW Document]. Dep. Environ. Food Rural Aff. URL https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file /283071/household-food-security-uk-140219.pdf (accessed 12.16.14). Lang T and Barling D (2012) Food security and food sustainability: reformulating the debate. The Geographical Journal 178(4): 313–326. Little, J., Austin, P., 1996. Women and the rural idyll. J. Rural Stud. 12, 101–111. Loo, C., 2014. Towards a More Participative Definition of Food Justice. J. Agric. Environ. Ethics 27, 787–809. MacMillan, T., Dowler, E., 2012. Just and sustainable? Examining the rhetoric and potential realities of UK food security. J. Agric. Environ. ethics 1–24. Marsden, T., 2013. From post-productionism to reflexive governance: Contested transitions in securing more sustainable food futures. J. Rural Stud. 29, 123–134. Martinez-Alier, J., 2014. The environmentalism of the poor. Geoforum 54, 239–241. Miller, D., 2008. National responsibility and global justice. Crit. Rev. Int. Soc. Polit. Philos. 11, 383–399. Minkoff-Zern, L.-A., 2014. Subsidizing farmworker hunger: Food assistance programs and the social reproduction of California farm labor. Geoforum 57, 91–98. Misselhorn A, Aggarwal P, Ericksen P, et al. (2012) A vision for attaining food security. Current Opinion in Environmental Sustainability 4(1): 7–17. Mooney, P.H., Hunt, S.A., 2009. Food Security: The Elaboration of Contested Claims to a Consensus Frame*. Rural Sociol. 74, 469–497. Moragues-Faus, A., 2016. Emancipatory or neoliberal food politics? Exploring the politics of collectivity of buying groups in the search for egalitarian food democracies. Antipode 49: 455–476 . Moragues-Faus, A., Morgan, K., 2015. Reframing the foodscape: the emergent world of urban food policy. Environ. Plan. A 47, 1558–1573. Murdoch, J., Lowe, P., Ward, N., Marsden, T., 2003. The Differentiated Countryside. Routledge , London. Nally, D., 2014. Governing precarious lives: land grabs, geopolitics, and food security. Geogr. J. n/a-n/a. Nelson, T., Clawson, R.A., Oxley, Z.M., 1997. Media framing of a civil liberties conflict and 36 its effect on tolerance. Am. Polit. Sci. Rev. 91, 567–583. Nussbaum, M., 2003. CAPABILITIES AS FUNDAMENTAL ENTITLEMENTS: SEN AND SOCIAL JUSTICE. Fem. Econ. 9, 33–59. O Connor, J., . Natural causes: Essays in ecological Marxism. Guilford Press, New York. Okereke, C., 2007. Global justice and neoliberal environmental governance: ethics, sustainable development and international co-operation. Routledge, London; New York. Oxfam and Church Action, 2013. Walking the Breadline: The scandal of food poverty in 21st-century Britain. Oxfam, 2013. The Power of People against Poverty. Accessed 01/03/2017 https://www.oxfam.org/sites/www.oxfam.org/files/oxfam-strategic-plan-2013- 2019.pdf Pan, Z., Kosicki, G., 1993. Framing analysis: An approach to news discourse. Polit. Commun. 10, 55–75. Pogge, T., 2002. Moral universalism and global economic justice, in: World Poverty and Human Rights: Cosmopolitan Responsibilities and Reforms. Polity Press, Cambridge, pp. 91–117. Rawls, J., 1999. The Law of Peoples. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts. Rawls, J., 1971. A theory of justice. Harvard University Press, Cambridge. Sampei, Y., Aoyagi-Usui, M., 2009. Mass-media coverage, its influence on public awareness of climate-change issues, and implications for Japan s national campaign to reduce greenhouse gas emissions. Glob. Environ. Chang. 19, 203–212. Sbicca, J., 2012. Growing food justice by planting an anti-oppression foundation: opportunities and obstacles for a budding social movement. Agric. Human Values 29, 455–466. Sen, A., 2009. The idea of justice. Harvard University Press, Harvard. Sikor, T., Newell, P., 2014. Globalizing environmental justice? Geoforum 54, 151–157. Singer, P., 1993. Practical Ethics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Smith, D.M., 2000. Social justice revisited. Environ. Plan. A 32, 1149–1162. doi:10.1068/a3258 Sonnino, R., Marsden, T., Moragues-Faus, A., 2016. Relationalities and convergences in food security narratives: towards a place-based approach. Trans. Inst. Br. Geogr. 41: 477–489 Sonnino, R., Moragues-Faus, A., Maggio, A., 2014. Sustainable Food Security: An Emerging Research and Policy Agenda. Int. J. Sociol. Agric. Food 21, 173–188. Unger, P., 1996. Living high and letting die: Our illusion of innocence. Oxford University Press, New York. Walker, P.A., 2006. Political ecology: where is the policy? Prog. Hum. Geogr. 30, 382– 37 395. Wells, R., Caraher, M., 2014. UK print media coverage of the food bank phenomenon: from food welfare to food charity? Br. Food J. 116, 1426–1445. Young, I., 2011. Responsibility for Justice. Oxford University Press, Oxford. Young, I., 2007. Global Challenges: War, Self- determination and Responsibility. Polity Press, Cambridge. Young, I., 2006. Responsibility and global justice: A social connection model. Soc. Philos. Policy. Young, I.M., 1990. Justice and the Politics of Difference. Princeton University press, Princeton. work_es6a3ejunjccxb4gkuktqvjl4a ---- Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 U.S. Department of Justice Office of Justice Programs Bureau of Justice Statistics BJS Mandatory P.L. 280 states Optional P.L. 280 states Indian reservations (U.S. Census Bureau) Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics Overview Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities Duren Banks, Steven W. Perry, and Allina Lee Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 Brian Reaves State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 Steven W. Perry, Ron Malega, and Duren Banks Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 Todd Minton Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System Mark Motivans and Howard Snyder Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 2 June 2011 Bureau of Justice Statistics James P. Lynch Director BJS Website: www.bjs.gov For information contact: BJS Clearinghouse 1-800-732-3277 The Bureau of Justice Statistics is the statistics agency of the U.S. Department of Justice. Duren Banks coordinated the development of this compendium. Contributing authors include Duren Banks, Allina Lee, Ron Malega, Todd Minton, Mark Motivans, Steven W. Perry, Brian Reaves, and Howard Snyder. In addition to the authors, other BJS staff who contributed to verification include Paul Guerino, Tracey Kyckelhahn, and Tracy L. Snell. Morgan Young and Jill Thomas edited the report, Barbara Quinn designed and produced the report, and Jayne Robinson and Tina Dorsey prepared the report for final printing under the supervision of Doris J. James. June 2011, NCJ 234459 3Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 BJS Mandatory P.L. 280 states Optional P.L. 280 states Indian reservations (U.S. Census Bureau) Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics Overview Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities Duren Banks, Steven W. Perry, and Allina Lee Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 Brian Reaves State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 Steven W. Perry, Ron Malega, and Duren Banks Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 Todd Minton Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System Mark Motivans and Howard Snyder 4 June 2011 Content s Overview 7 Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities 9 The Tribal Law and Order Act, 2010 (TLOA; Pub. L. No. 111-211, 124 Stat. 2258, Section 251(b)) requires the Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS) to establish and implement a tribal data collection system and to support tribal participation in national records and information systems. This is the first BJS report on the status of tribal data collection activities as required by the act. It describes BJS’s activities between July 2010 and June 2011 to improve tribal law enforcement reporting to the FBI’s Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) and BJS’s direct collaboration with tribal criminal justice systems to collect data about tribal court systems. It summarizes data published by BJS on jails in Indian country, tribal law enforcement agencies, state prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction in Indian country, tribal youth in the federal justice system, and reporting to the UCR. It describes activities and funding opportunities to improve tribal crime data collection through programs such as the National Criminal History Improvement Program (NCHIP), the National Instant Criminal Background Check System (NICS), Byrne/JAG funding, and UCR training. Table 1.1. Tribes submitting crime data to the Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) Program and receiving Byrne/Justice Assistance Grant (JAG) awards, FY 2008-2010 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10 Table 1.2. Bureau of Justice Statistics planned program activities in response to the Tribal Law and Order Act . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 13 Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 15 Presents data on tribal law enforcement agencies from the 2008 Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies. This report defines the number and locations of tribal law enforcement agencies, service populations, and the number of sworn and nonsworn employees. It describes agency participation in traditional law enforcement (routine patrol, criminal investigation, and dispatching calls for service), public safety functions (emergency management, animal control, and fire services), specialized functions (search and rescue, tactical operations, and underwater recovery), and court-related activities (executing arrest warrants, enforcing protection orders, and serving process). The report details participation in multiagency task forces involving drug and human trafficking, gangs, violent crime, and antiterrorism. It presents data on community outreach efforts, such as school resource officers and community policing officers. Table 2.1. Tribally operated law enforcement agencies, by type of agency and number of full-time sworn personnel, 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 16 Table 2.2. The 25 largest tribally operated law enforcement agencies, by the number of full-time sworn personnel, 2008. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17 Table 2.3. Use of community policing and school resource officers by tribal police departments, 2000 and 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 18 Figure 2.1. Location of tribally operated law enforcement agencies, 2008 . 15 Figure 2.2. Selected law enforcement functions performed by tribal police departments, 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 18 Figure 2.3. Selected court-related functions performed by tribal police departments, 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 18 Figure 2.4. Selected special functions performed by tribal police departments, 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 19 Figure 2.5. Task force participation of tribal police departments, 2008 . . . 19 State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 21 Describes state prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction in Indian country under Public Law 83-280 (P.L. 280). This report examines the activities of prosecutors’ offices in states affected by P.L. 280 through either mandatory or optional jurisdiction. Six states have mandatory jurisdiction under P.L. 280 over crimes in Indian country: Alaska, California, Minnesota (except the Red Lake Reservation), Nebraska, Oregon (except the Warm Springs Reservation), and Wisconsin. The report also examines activities of prosecutors’ offices in the 10 states that have an option to assume jurisdiction over crimes in Indian country within their borders: Arizona, Florida, Idaho, Iowa, Montana, Nevada, North Dakota, South Dakota, Utah, and Washington. Using data from the 2007 National Census of State Court Prosecutors, this report describes the characteristics of state prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction for crimes committed in Indian country, including budgets, staffing, and caseload. It also examines the types of offenses committed in Indian country that were prosecuted in 2007. Table 3.1. Number of tribes participating in the Census of Tribal Justice Agencies in Indian Country, by P.L. 280 status, type of court systems, and state, 2002 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 22 Table 3.2. State prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction for crimes committed in Indian country, by P.L. 280 status, 2007 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 22 Table 3.3. Type of state prosecutors’ offices in Indian country, by P.L. 280 status, 2007. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 25 Table 3.4. Budget, staffing, and caseload of state prosecutors’ offices, by P.L. 280 status, 2007 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 25 Figure 3.1. State prosecutors’ offices reporting jurisdiction in Indian country under P.L. 280, 2007 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 23 Figure 3.2. State prosecutors’ offices reporting prosecution of specific crimes in Indian country, by P.L. 280 status, 2007 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 24 5Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 Contents (continued) Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 27 Presents selected findings from the bulletin Jails in Indian Country, 2009, released in February 2011 (NCJ232223). Data are based on an enumeration of 80 jails, confinement facilities, detention centers, and other facilities operated by tribal authorities or the Bureau of Indian Affairs (BIA) reported to the annual Survey of Jails in Indian Country. The report includes data on the number of adults and juveniles held, type of offense, number of persons confined on the last weekday of each month, average daily population, peak population, and admissions in June 2009. It also summarizes rated capacity, facility crowding, and jail staffing. Table 4.1. Inmates, rated capacity, and percent of capacity occupied in Indian country jails, 2004 and 2007-2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 28 Table 4.2. Jails in Indian country that held the majority of inmates in 2009 compared to 2008, by facility . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 28 Table 4.3. Number of Indian country jails, by percent of rated capacity occupied, June 2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 29 Table 4.4. Admissions and expected length of stay in Indian country jails during June, by facility size, June 2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 30 Table 4.5. Number of inmates confined in Indian country jails, by demographic characteristics, conviction status, and offense, midyear 2000, 2002, 2004, and 2007-2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 31 Table 4.6. Number of persons employed in Indian country jails, by job function, June 30, 2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 32 Figure 4.1. Inmates confined in Indian country jails, at midyear 2000-2004 and 2007-2009. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 27 Figure 4.2. Percent of rated capacity occupied, by type of inmate count, June 2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 29 Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 35 Presents findings on tribal youth processed through the federal criminal justice system between 1999 and 2008. Findings are from a recent study conducted by the Urban Institute under the Bureau of Justice Statistics’ Federal Justice Statistics Program (FJSP). This report describes the number of tribal youth in the federal system and examines how they are handled through the stages of the federal criminal case process, from arrest to confinement. It describes tribal youth demographic characteristics, offenses, and case outcomes, such as referrals for prosecution, dismissal rates, sentencing, and time served. Table 5.1. Reason for matters declined for prosecution with tribal youth suspects, 2005-2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 37 Table 5.2. Federally recognized tribes and enrolled members, 2005. . . . . 38 Table 5.3. Tribal and non-tribal youth admitted to the Federal Bureau of Prisons, by offense type, 1944-2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 41 Figure 5.1. Tribal youth referred to and prosecuted by U.S. attorneys, 2000-2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 35 Figure 5.2. Case-related reasons for declination, 2005-2008 . . . . . . . . . 37 Figure 5.3. Tribal youth admitted to the custody of federal prison authorities, and five federal judicial districts that committed the majority of tribal youth, 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 38 Figure 5.4. Maximum time in federal custody of juveniles adjudicated delinquent . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 39 Figure 5.5. Tribal youth in the Federal Bureau of Prisons, by status, at admission, 2000-2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40 Figure 5.6. Non-tribal youth admitted to the Federal Bureau of Prisons, by status, at admission, 2000-2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40 Figure 5.7. Non-tribal youth admitted to the custody of federal prison authorities, and five federal judicial districts that committed the majority of tribal youth, 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 42 Highlights Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities 9 � The Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS) consulted with tribal leaders through a variety of forums in 2010. � For the first time, the Bureau of Indian Affairs’ (BIA) submissions to the Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) were disaggregated by tribe and reported in Crime in the U.S., 2009. � The number of tribes eligible for Byrne/JAG funding increased from 5 to 22. � In 2008, 140 tribal law enforcement staff received UCR training. � BJS provided competitive funding opportunities for jurisdictions to improve criminal records. � BJS developed a multifaceted data collection system that both established new collections and enhanced current programs. 6 June 2011 Highlights (continued) Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 15 � Tribally operated law enforcement agencies employed nearly 4,600 full-time personnel, including about 3,000 sworn officers. � The largest tribal law enforcement agency, the Navajo Police Department, employed 393 full-time sworn personnel in Arizona, New Mexico, and Utah. � Eleven of the 25 largest tribal law enforcement agencies served jurisdictions covering more than 1,000 square miles. � Overall, tribal police departments cost about $257 per resident to operate during fiscal year 2008. � In addition to law enforcement functions, nearly all tribal police departments performed court-related functions, such as court security and serving process. � More than half of tribal police departments used community policing officers, and more than a third used school resource officers. � About 4 in 5 tribal police departments participated in one or more multiagency task forces. State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 21 � Ninety-three state court prosecutors’ offices in the 16 P.L. 280 states reported jurisdiction for felonies committed in Indian country under P.L. 280. � Seventy-three percent of offices with jurisdiction in Indian country reported prosecuting at least one felony case committed in Indian country. � Most offices in P.L. 280 states prosecuted at least one offense involving drugs (63%), domestic violence (60%), or aggravated assault (58%). � Eighteen offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states with jurisdiction for Indian country prosecuted at least one rape, and 12 offices prosecuted a homicide. � Of state prosecutors’ offices that reported jurisdiction for felony cases in Indian country under P.L. 280, 70% served judicial districts with populations of less than 100,000 residents. � Offices with jurisdiction for felony crimes committed in Indian country had an average operating budget of $5.2 million in 2007. Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 27 � The number of inmates confined in Indian country jails increased by 1.9% between midyear 2008 and 2009, reaching 2,176 inmates. � Between June 2008 and June 2009, the average daily jail population in Indian country increased by 12%, and the percentage of occupied bed space increased from 64.2% to 73.5%. � Eleven jails (14% of all facilities) held 51% of inmates confined at midyear 2009. � During June 2009, the number of inmates admitted to Indian country jails (11,357) was about 5 times the size of the average daily population (2,124). � The expected average length of stay increased by a half day from 5.1 days during June 2008 to 5.6 days during June 2009. � Indian country jail authorities reported no deaths in custody between July 1, 2008, and June 30, 2009, down from 4 reported deaths during the 12-month period ending June 30, 2008. � Attempted suicides by inmates declined from 78 in 2008 to 56 in 2009. � Indian country jails held fewer inmates for domestic violence at midyear 2009 (252), continuing the downward trend in the number held for this offense since 2007 (362). � The percentage of certified correctional officers working in Indian country jails increased steadily, from 63% at midyear 2007 to 79% at midyear 2009. Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 35 � In 2008, relatively few juveniles were referred to federal prosecutors (315 out of 178,570 suspects) or admitted to federal prison jurisdiction (156 out 71,663 offenders). � Tribal youth (70) comprised nearly half of juveniles (152) handled by the federal courts in 2008. � Federal judicial districts of Arizona, Montana, South Dakota, New Mexico, and North Dakota accounted for 94% of tribal youth investigated, 92% of those prosecuted, and 88% of those admitted to federal prison jurisdiction in 2008. � In 2008, about 72% of tribal youth were investigated for violent offenses, including sexual abuse (35%), assault (20%), and murder (17%). � About 40% of matters involving tribal youth were declined by federal prosecutors in 2008. � A greater share of cases involving tribal youth in U.S. district courts were terminated by conviction (91%) than by dismissal (9%). � From 1994 to 2008, the lowest number of tribal (72) and non-tribal youth (84) admitted to the jurisdiction of federal prison authorities occurred in 2008. � Admissions to federal prison jurisdiction among tribal youth declined 10% per year from 1999 to 2008, while non-tribal youth admissions declined 12% per year. � In 2008, tribal youth served an average of 26 months under federal jurisdiction, which was more than double the tribal justice system maximum sentence of 12 months. 7Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 Overview The Tribal Law and Order Act (TLOA), enacted July 29, 2010, requires the Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS) to (1) establish and implement a tribal data collection system and (2) support tribal participation in national records and information systems (P.L. 111-211, 124 Stat. 2258, § 251(b)). The act further requires the director of BJS to consult with Indian tribes to establish and implement this data collection system. The BJS director is required to report to Congress within one year of enactment, and annually thereafter, the data collected and analyzed in accordance with the act. This report describes activities in support of BJS’s tribal crime data collection system and summarizes findings published from that system between July 2010 and June 2011. Multifaceted data collection system Criminal jurisdiction in Indian country—federally recognized reservations, tribal communities, and identified trust lands—varies by the type of crime committed, whether the offender or victim was a tribal member, and the state in which the offense occurred. Due to the sovereign status of federally recognized tribes in the United States, crimes committed in Indian country are often subject to concurrent jurisdiction between multiple criminal justice agencies. Public Law 83-280 (P.L. 280) gave select states legal jurisdiction over tribal members to prosecute crimes that occur on the reservation under existing state laws. These mandatory P.L. 280 states include California, Minnesota (except the Red Lake Reservation), Nebraska, Oregon (except the Warm Springs Reservation), Wisconsin, and Alaska. P.L. 280 permitted other states to acquire jurisdiction over crimes committed in Indian country at their option. These optional P.L. 280 states assume jurisdiction, either in whole or in part, over Indian country within their boundaries, and include Arizona, Florida, Idaho, Iowa, Montana, Nevada, North Dakota, South Dakota, Utah, and Washington. In the remaining states, where P.L. 280 does not apply, federal and tribal governments maintain concurrent jurisdiction for major crimes committed in Indian country (as defined in the Major Crimes Act and subsequent amendments (18 U.S.C. § 1153)). Tribal governments have jurisdiction for all other crimes committed in Indian country that involve both an Indian offender and Indian victim. States retain jurisdiction for non-Indian crimes committed in Indian country—those in which neither the offender nor the victim is a tribal member. Due in part to these jurisdictional complexities, existing tribal data systems are often limited in scope and applicable only to certain jurisdictions or states. An effective tribal data collection system will include data from federal, state, local, and tribal agencies. The information maintained in this system should further be considered in light of the concurrent jurisdictional roles multiple agencies maintain in Indian country. Recent findings from the tribal data collection system 178 tribal law enforcement agencies operated in 2008 In September 2008, American Indian tribes operated 178 law enforcement agencies. These 178 agencies employed at least one full-time sworn officer with general arrest powers or the equivalent in part-time officers. The total includes 157 general purpose tribal police departments and 21 special jurisdiction agencies tasked with enforcing natural resources laws that pertain primarily to hunting and fishing on tribal lands. Tribes operated law enforcement agencies in 28 states and employed about 3,000 full-time sworn personnel. Eleven of the 25 largest tribal law enforcement agencies served jurisdictions of more than 1,000 square miles. (See Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008, page 15, for more information.) 83 tribal law enforcement agencies provided data through the Bureau of Indian Affairs (BIA) that met the FBI’s guidelines for publication Offenses known to tribal law enforcement agencies were reported by tribal agencies in the FBI’s Crime in the United States, 2009. Eighty-three tribal law enforcement agencies met FBI guidelines for data publication in the report.* Nearly 3,800 violent crimes and approximately 11,400 property crimes were known to *Crimes known to tribal law enforcement agencies are submitted to the UCR through the BIA. UCR data must be submitted by local law enforcement with a valid reporting number, and be complete for all 12 months of the year. Data submitted to the UCR must also meet FBI data quality guidelines for publication in Crime in the U.S. 8 June 2011 these selected tribal law enforcement agencies in 2009. (See the FBI’s Crime in the United States, 2009, http:// www2.fbi.gov/ucr/cius2009/data/ table_11.html, for more information.) 93 state prosecutors’ offices in P.L. 280 states reported jurisdiction for felonies committed in Indian country In 2007, 93 state court prosecutors’ offices reported jurisdiction under P.L. 280 for felonies committed in Indian country. Seventy-three percent of these offices reported prosecuting at least one felony case that arose from Indian country in 2007, including at least one offense that involved drugs (63%), domestic violence (60%), or aggravated assault (58%). Most state prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction under P.L. 280 served districts with 100,000 or fewer residents. (See State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007, page 21, for more information.) Jails in Indian country housed 2,176 inmates in 2009 The number of inmates confined in Indian country jails increased by 1.9% between midyear 2008 and midyear 2009, from 2,135 to 2,176 inmates. Over the 12 months ending June 2009, the average daily jail population in Indian country increased by 12%, and the percentage of occupied bed space increased from 64.2% to 73.5%. (See Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009, page 27, for more information.) Most tribal youth in the federal system were referred for violent offenses Between 1999 and 2008, 65% of tribal youth in criminal matters received by federal prosecutors were referred for a violent offense. Sexual abuse was the most common violent offense, followed by assault and murder. In 2008, federal prosecutors received 129 tribal youth suspects in matters opened out of 178,570 total matters investigated. Tribal youth admitted to the legal custody of federal prison authorities were mostly male (90%) and tended to be older teens; more than two-thirds were between the ages 16 and 17. (See Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System, page 35, for more information.) 9Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities, 2011 The Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS), in collaboration with other federal agencies and American Indian tribes, conducted several activities to develop the tribal data collection system as of June 2011. The data collection system establishes both new data collections and enhances current programs to carry out the requirements of the Tribal Law and Order Act (TLOA), 2010. BJS focused on improving tribal law enforcement reporting to the FBI’s Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) and developed direct data collection from tribal criminal justice systems, such as collecting information about the nature and operation of tribal court systems. Efforts also include activities and funding opportunities to improve tribal crime data collection through programs such as the National Criminal History Improvement Program (NCHIP), the National Instant Criminal Background Check System (NICS), Byrne/JAG funding, and UCR training. Activities to Support Tribal Crime Data Collection Systems, July 2010 through June 2011 Tribal consultations conducted in 2010 BJS consulted with tribal leaders through a variety of forums in 2010. BJS developed and distributed an initial plan that responded to the TLOA sections that directly referenced tribal crime data collection. This plan was presented to several stakeholder groups to invite feedback and input, including— � Interdepartmental Tribal Justice Safety and Wellness Consultation, Session 12 (December 2010, Palm Springs, CA) � Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) trainings for tribal law enforcement (2010) agencies � National Congress of American Indians, 2011 Executive Council Winter Meeting (March 2011, Washington, DC). For the first time, the Bureau of Indian Affairs’ (BIA) submissions to UCR were disaggregated by tribe and reported in the FBI’s Crime in the U.S., 2009 Working with the Office of Justice Services in the BIA, and the Office of Tribal Justice and the FBI in the Department of Justice (DOJ), BJS developed a process to support tribal access to, and input in, regional and national criminal justice databases, including the National Crime Information Center (NCIC) and the Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR). As a result of this process, data provided to the FBI from the BIA were able to be disaggregated by tribe. Offenses known to tribal law enforcement agencies were reported by tribal agencies in the FBI’s Crime in the United States, 2009. Eighty- three tribal law enforcement agencies met FBI guidelines for data to be published in the report. Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities, 2011 Duren Banks, Ph.D., and Steven W. Perry, BJS Statisticians Allina Lee, BJS Policy Analyst U.S. Department of Justice Office of Justice Programs Bureau of Justice Statistics June 2011, NCJ 234518 Highlights � The Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS) consulted with tribal leaders through a variety of forums in 2010. � For the first time, the Bureau of Indian Affairs’ (BIA) submissions to the Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) were disaggregated by tribe and reported in Crime in the U.S., 2009. � The number of tribes eligible for Byrne/JAG funding increased from 5 in 2008 to 22 in 2010. � In 2010, 140 tribal law enforcement staff received UCR training. � BJS provided competitive funding opportunities for jurisdictions to improve criminal records in fiscal year 2011. � BJS developed a multifaceted data collection system that both established new collections and enhanced current programs. 10 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 The number of tribes eligible for Byrne/ JAG funding increased from 5 in fiscal year 2008 to 22 in fiscal year 2010 Collaborative efforts between the departments of Justice and Interior have increased the number of tribes reporting monthly crime data to the UCR, thereby increasing the number of tribes eligible to receive Byrne/JAG awards. Byrne/JAG funds can be used to support a range of activities in seven broad program areas, including law enforcement; prosecution and courts; crime prevention and education; corrections; drug treatment and enforcement; program planning, evaluation, and technology improvement; and crime victim and witness programs. Most American Indian tribes had been ineligible to receive Byrne/JAG funds because of gaps in Indian country crime statistics and traditional methods for reporting data. Prior to 2009, BIA provided an aggregate number of crimes known to tribal law enforcement to the UCR. Since these data could not be disaggregated by tribe, tribal law enforcement agencies that did not submit information directly to the UCR were not eligible for Byrne/JAG awards. In FY 2008, 25 tribes submitted crime data directly to the FBI, with 5 of the tribes eligible to receive Byrne/JAG awards totaling $150,000. In FY 2010, the number of tribes that submitted crime data increased to 144 following collaborative efforts between agencies in the departments of Justice and Interior, with 22 tribes eligible for Byrne/JAG awards totaling $709,000 (table 1.1). More than 140 tribal law enforcement staff received UCR training Through Recovery Act funds, BJS developed and implemented the Tribal Crime Data project to further support the reporting of tribal crime to the UCR, and thereby establish eligibility for Byrne/ JAG funds. The project is also part of BJS’s larger effort to collect more reliable information on American Indians in the criminal justice system and crimes committed in Indian country. Through the Tribal Crime Data project, BJS conducted three training sessions in 2010, with more than 140 tribal members, on the use of the UCR systems. In 2011 the project provided training and technical assistance to tribes that did not meet FBI data quality guidelines or had not previously submitted complete crime data to BIA. Table 1.1 Tribes submitting crime data to the Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) and receiving Justice Assistance Grant (JAG) awards, FY 2008–2010 Number of tribes— Fiscal Year Reporting to UCR Eligible for JAG award Eligible award amount 2008 25 5 $150,000 2009 106 20 559,000 2010 144 22 709,000 BJS, acting jointly with the Office of Justice Services, BIA (DOI), and the FBI (DOJ), will work with tribes and tribal law enforcement to establish and implement tribal data collection systems (P.L. 111-211 § 251(b)). 11Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities, 2011 Funding for improving criminal records To improve criminal records, BJS provided outreach to agencies in tribal jurisdictions through two competitive funding opportunities: � National Criminal History Improvement Program (NCHIP) solicitation, 2011 � National Instant Criminal Background Check System (NICS) Act Record Improvement Program (NARIP) solicitation, 2011. The TLOA made federally recognized tribes eligible for awards under BJS’s NCHIP. State and tribal entities apply for NCHIP funds to enhance the crime fighting and criminal justice capabilities of governments by improving the accuracy, utility, and interstate accessibility of criminal history records. Jurisdictions also apply for NCHIP funds to enhance records of protective orders that involve domestic violence and stalking, sex offender records, automated identification systems, and other state systems that support national records systems and their use for criminal history background checks. BJS released the FY 2011 NCHIP solicitation on January 13, 2011, and collaborated with other OJP components to disseminate information about the NCHIP funding announcement as broadly as possible. Tribal contacts were alerted via email to the funding opportunity, and the solicitation was posted to the BJS and DOJ Tribal Safety and Justice websites. Information about the NCHIP funding opportunity was also presented during several meetings and a consultation in the fall and winter of 2010. Additionally, BJS developed an addendum to the solicitation that identified priority funding areas and eligibility requirements for tribal applicants. The addendum outlined key tribal priority areas activities related to— � information technology systems to capture and transmit tribal issued domestic violence and stalking records to the FBI NCIC Protection Order File � automation and transmission of existing qualifying domestic violence and stalking records to the FBI NCIC Protection Order File. The NARIP implements the provisions of the NICS Improvement Amendments Act of 2007, enacted in the wake of the shooting tragedy at Virginia Tech and includes tribes as eligible entities. The NARIP funds provide assistance to eligible states and tribes to improve the completeness, automation, and transmittal of records needed by the NICS to identify persons prohibited from receiving or possessing a firearm. These records include prohibited mental health adjudications and commitments, felony convictions, felony indictments, fugitives from justice, drug arrests and convictions, domestic violence protection orders, and misdemeanor crimes of domestic violence. BJS will award FY 2011 NARIP funds to support efforts to improve the records used by NICS, by providing assistance to states and tribes to improve the completeness, automation, and transmittal of records to state and federal systems. BJS released the FY 2011 NARIP solicitation on March 15, 2011. The same process used to disseminate information about the NCHIP funding opportunity was followed to alert tribes to the NARIP solicitation. Subject to the availability of appropriated funds and any modifications or additional requirements that may be imposed by law, BJS plans to competitively award NCHIP and NARIP funds in FY 2011. Eligible applications will be evaluated and scored by peer reviewers, and funding will be made based on the selection criteria outlined in the solicitations. BJS is authorized to provide for improvements in the accuracy, quality, timeliness, immediate accessibility, and integration of state and tribal criminal history and related records (P.L. 111-211 § 251(b)(1)(H)). 12 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 BJS established new collections and enhanced current programs In addition to collaborating with other federal agencies to improve tribal law enforcement reporting to the UCR, BJS developed a plan to collect information about tribal criminal justice systems. This multipronged approach both established new collections and enhanced current programs that serve the purposes of the TLOA. Through its ongoing statistical projects, BJS provided information on (1) suspects and defendants processed in the federal criminal justice system, including federal prosecutions of crimes committed in Indian country, (2) the incidence of crimes known to law enforcement that occur on tribal reservations or were reported by Indian country law enforcement authorities, (3) the characteristics of tribal law enforcement agencies, and (4) the characteristics of jails in Indian country. BJS plans to begin collecting information about the nature and operation of tribal court systems in 2012 (table 1.2). Survey of Tribal Court Systems BJS developed the Survey of Tribal Court Systems to build on BJS’s previous Census of Tribal Justice Agencies (See Census of Tribal Justice Agencies in Indian Country, 2002, BJS Web, December 2005). The survey will gather administrative and operational information from tribal courts, prosecutors’ offices, and indigent defense providers operating in the estimated 190 federally recognized tribal justice systems in the U.S. Subject to the availability of appropriated funds and any modifications or additional requirements that may be imposed by law, BJS plans to award the Survey of Tribal Court Systems in FY 2011. BJS will work with the awardee and collaborating organizations to develop the data collection instrument and methodology. The instrument will include, at a minimum, measures of tribal court organization, court caseload, characteristics of prosecutors in tribal courts, and systems to provide indigent defense in tribal courts. Based on the results of the initial data collection, BJS will devise a strategy for conducting a regular data collection program among Indian country court systems. Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies The Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies provides data on staffing, functions, and expenditures. Data collected include the number of sworn and civilian personnel by state and type of agency, and functions performed by each agency. BJS analyzed and published findings from data collected in 2008, from the Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies program, including 178 tribal law enforcement agencies. Survey of Jails in Indian Country The Survey of Jails in Indian Country data describe jails, confinement facilities, detention centers, and other facilities operated by tribal authorities or BIA. The annual report from the Survey of Jails in Indian Country includes data on the number of adults and juveniles held, type of offense, number of persons confined on the last weekday of each month, average daily population, peak population, and admissions at midyear. It also summarizes rated capacity, facility crowding, and jail staffing. The most recent report that describes findings from the 2009 survey was released in February 2011. National Census of State Court Prosecutors In 2007 BJS conducted the National Census of State Prosecutors, which was the second complete enumeration of all chief prosecutors who tried felony cases in state courts of general jurisdiction. The census collected information about whether district The director of BJS will establish and implement a tribal data collection system (P.L. 111-211 § 251(b)). 13Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities, 2011 Table 1.2 Bureau of Justice Statistics Planned Program Activities in Response to the Tribal Law and Order Act Program Objective Timeline Collaboration with DOJ Components and BIA To increase the number of tribes eligible to receive Edward Byrne Memorial Justice Assistance Grant (JAG) Program funds, ensure tribal access to regional and national databases, and develop comprehensive tribal crime data systems. Ongoing. BJS Recovery Act Program To support tribes to more accurately and consistently report tribal crime data to the BIA and/or the FBI through technical assistance, training, and information sharing. Crimes known to some tribal law enforcement agencies published in Crime in the United States, 2009 and annually thereafter. Grants to Support Tribal Participation in Regional and National Databases To continue to include federally-recognized tribes as eligible entities for the National Instant Criminal Background Check System (NICS) Act Record Improvement Program and add federally- recognized tribes as eligible entities to the National Criminal History Improvement Program (NCHIP) grant awards. Tribes are eligible for awards as of FY 2009 (NICS) and FY 2011 (NCHIP). Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies To collect data from all state, local, and tribal law enforcement agencies on staffing, expenditures and functions. BJS will continue to implement strategies designed to accurately represent the work of tribal law enforcement agencies. Periodically since 1992. Latest report: 2004 census 2008 census report in 2011. Survey of Tribal Court Systems To gather administrative and operational information from tribal courts, prosecutors’ offices, and indigent defense providers. Award: August 2011. Design and Data Collection: 2011-2012. Analysis and Reporting: Early 2013. Survey of Jails in Indian Country The survey is an annual enumeration of jails, confinement facilities, detention centers, and other facilities operated by tribal authorities or the BIA. Data are collected intermittently via an addendum to the core survey on the physical conditions and operations of Indian country facilities. The addendum requests information on inmate medical services, mental health services, suicide prevention procedures, substance dependency programs, domestic violence counseling, sex offender treatment, education programs, and inmate work assignments. Annually since 1998. Latest report: 2009 survey 2010 survey report expected in 2011. Federal Justice Statistics Program To compile comprehensive information describing suspects and defendants processed in the federal criminal justice system. Ongoing since 1998. Annual data through 2009 available on the BJS website. BJS Native American Crime Information Website To provide users with easy-to-access and current information from existing and new data collection programs Design and populate website: 2010-2011. Public release: Late 2011. 14 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 attorney offices have jurisdiction for prosecuting felony cases occurring in Indian country under P.L. 280, and what types of crimes the office prosecuted. The findings from this data collection are in State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country on page 21. Federal Justice Statistics Program The Federal Justice Statistics Program (FJSP) provides comprehensive and detailed information about the federal justice system’s processing of criminal cases. The FJSP provides annual data on workload, activities, and outcomes associated with federal criminal cases. Information is acquired on all aspects of processing in the federal justice system, including arrests, prosecution decisions, referrals to magistrates, court dispositions, sentencing outcomes, sentence length, and time served. The FJSP receives the source data from the U.S. Marshals Service, Drug Enforcement Administration, Executive Office of U.S. Attorneys, Administrative Office of the U.S. Courts, U.S. Sentencing Commission, and the Federal Bureau of Prisons. BJS is currently developing research projects that will examine American Indian defendants who are processed in the federal justice system. Findings from the first of these projects, describing characteristics of American Indian youth who are processed in the federal criminal justice system, are in the Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System on page 35. References Crime in the United States, 2009, U.S. Department of Justice, Federal Bureau of Investigation, September 2010. Jails in Indian Country, 2009, NCJ 232223, BJS Web, February 2011. State Prosecutors Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007, NCJ 234241, BJS Web, June 2011. Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008. NCJ 234217, BJS Web, June 2011. Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System, NCJ 234218, BJS Web, June 2011. Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 15 Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 Brian A. Reaves, Ph.D., BJS Statistician In September 2008, American Indian tribes operated 178 law enforcement agencies that employed at least one full-time sworn officer with general arrest powers or the equivalent in part-time officers. The total includes 157 general purpose tribal police departments and 21 special jurisdiction agencies tasked with enforcing natural resources laws that pertain primarily to hunting and fishing on tribal lands. Collectively, tribes operated law enforcement agencies in 28 states. Washington (24), Arizona (22), Oklahoma (19), and New Mexico (17) had the largest numbers of tribal law enforcement agencies (figure 2.1). These findings are based on the 2008 Bureau of Justice Statistics’ (BJS) Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies. In addition to tribally operated agencies, the Department of the Interior’s (DOI) Bureau of Indian Affairs (BIA) operated 42 agencies that provided law enforcement Highlights � Tribally operated law enforcement agencies employed nearly 4,600 full-time personnel, including about 3,000 sworn officers. � The largest tribal law enforcement agency, the Navajo Police Department, employed 393 full-time sworn personnel in Arizona, New Mexico, and Utah. � Eleven of the 25 largest tribal law enforcement agencies served jurisdictions covering more than 1,000 square miles. � Overall, tribal police departments cost about $257 per resident to operate during FY 2008. � In addition to law enforcement functions, nearly all tribal police departments performed court-related functions, such as court security and serving process. � More than half of tribal police departments used community policing officers, and more than a third used school resource officers. � About 4 in 5 tribal police departments participated in one or more multiagency task forces. U.S. Department of Justice Office of Justice Programs Bureau of Justice Statistics June 2011 NCJ 234217 No tribally operated LE agencies Under 5 agencies 5-9 agencies 10 or more agencies Figure 2.1 Location of tribally operated law enforcement agencies, 2008 Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics, Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies, 2008 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201116 services in Indian country. Nationwide, BIA employed 277 full-time sworn personnel in 2008. Along with direct oversight of its own programs, BIA also provided technical assistance and some oversight to tribally operated agencies. On the more than 300 federal Indian reservation areas in the U.S., police officers may be tribal, federal, state, county, or municipal employees. Some areas may be served by more than one type of officer. Commonly, tribal police department funding, administration, and employees are based on the Indian Self-Determination and Education Assistance Act of 1975, (Public Law 93-638 or P.L. 638). This law allowed tribes to assume responsibility for many programs previously administered by the federal government, including law enforcement. P.L. 638 agencies operate with tribal employees under contract and with financial assistance from the BIA. Tribally operated agencies can also function under a self-governance compact with the BIA. This arrangement provides block grant payments, allowing for more tribal control than the line item funding of P.L. 638 contracts. Full tribal control over law enforcement services exists where such services are entirely funded by the tribal government. Jurisdiction over offenses in Indian country may lie with federal, state, or tribal agencies, depending on the offense, offender, victim, and offense location. Most tribes have cross- deputization agreements, often with neighboring nontribal agencies. These agreements allow law enforcement personnel from state, local, and tribal entities to cross jurisdictions in criminal cases, and can be used to enhance law enforcement capabilities in areas where state and tribal lands are contiguous and intermingled. In some instances, the number of agreements is large. For example, the Cherokee Nation Marshal Service is cross-deputized with 50 municipal, county, state, and federal agencies. Tribal police departments employed 2.3 full-time officers per 1,000 residents In September 2008, the 178 operating tribal law enforcement agencies employed more than 4,500 full- time personnel, including about 3,000 sworn officers (table 2.1). The 157 general purpose tribal police departments employed 4,294 full-time personnel, including 2,835 sworn officers and 1,459 civilian personnel. These agencies employed an additional 129 part-time personnel, including 80 sworn officers (not shown in table). The 21 natural resources agencies employed 271 full-time personnel, including 164 sworn officers and 107 civilian employees. These natural resources agencies also employed 11 part-time personnel, including 7 sworn officers (not shown in table). General purpose tribal police departments had a combined service population of about 1.2 million residents.* This corresponds to about 2.3 full-time sworn officers per 1,000 residents, which was the national average for all local police departments as of 2007. (See Local Police Departments, 2007, BJS Web, December 2010.) Collectively, tribal police departments cost $257 per resident to operate for 2008 (not shown in table). In 2007 the national average for all local police departments was $260 per resident. *Based on the American Indian service population counts published in BIA’s American Indian Population and Labor Force Report, 2005. The service population is the total number of enrolled tribal members and members from other tribes who live on or near the reservation and are eligible to use the BIA- funded tribal services. The service population excludes any non-Indian residents served by a tribally operated law enforcement agency and other persons using roads, stores, casinos, and other public places on tribal land. Table 2.1 Tribally operated law enforcement agencies, by type of agency and number of full-time sworn personnel, 2008 Type of agency and number of full-time sworn personnel Number of agencies Number of full-time employees Total Sworn Civilian All agencies 178 4,565 2,999 1,566 General purpose police departments Total 157 4,294 2,835 1,459 50 or more 6 1,397 871 526 25-49 19 955 607 348 10-24 61 1,380 955 425 5-9 47 479 332 147 Under 5 24 83 70 13 Natural resources agencies Total 21 271 164 107 10-24 8 154 107 47 5-9 4 38 29 9 Under 5 9 79 28 51 Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 17 11 of the 25 largest tribal law enforcement agencies served jurisdictions of more than 1,000 square miles The 25 largest tribally operated agencies employed at least 25 full- time sworn personnel. The largest agency, the Navajo Police Department, employed 393 full-time officers to serve tribal lands in Arizona, New Mexico, and Utah (table 2.2). The next largest were the Seminole Police Department (Florida) with 144 officers, and the Salt River Police Department (Arizona) with 125 officers. The BIA service population for the 25 largest agencies ranged from less than 1,000 to about 200,000 residents. Although not all reservations are open to the public, many tribal law enforcement agencies deal with a significant number of daily visitors in addition to the resident population. The natural resources of tribal lands attract visitors, as do conference facilities and casinos. All of the 25 largest agencies had at least one casino operating within their jurisdictional area. The amount of land area served by a tribal law enforcement agency can be quite large. For example, the Navajo Police Department has jurisdiction over about 22,000 square miles, a larger land area than any county in the continental United States. Ten other agencies among the 25 largest had jurisdictional areas exceeding 1,000 square miles, a larger land area than any city in the continental United States. Table 2.2 The 25 largest tribally operated law enforcement agencies, by the number of full-time sworn personnel, 2008 Name and location of agency Number of full-time sworn personnel BIA service population, 2005 Full-time sworn personnel per 1,000 residents Reservation land area (square miles) Full-time sworn personnel per 25 square miles Navajo Police Department (AZ, NM, UT) 393 192,067 2.0 22,174 0.4 Seminole Police Department (FL) 144 3,165 45.5 141 25.5 Salt River Police Department (AZ) 125 7,313 17.1 81 38.6 Gila River Indian Community Police Department (AZ) 93 14,966 6.2 584 4.0 Tohono O’odham Police Department (AZ) 66 26,673 2.5 4,453 0.4 Choctaw Police Department (MS) 50 8,313 6.0 25 50.0 Oglala Sioux Tribe Department of Public Safety (SD) 49 43,146 1.1 3,159 0.4 Cherokee Indian Police Department (NC) 45 13,562 3.3 83 13.6 Muscogee (Creek) Nation Lighthorse Tribal Police (OK) 39 55,817 0.7 4,648 0.2 Miccosukee Police Department (FL) 36 589 61.1 128 7.0 Poarch Creek Tribal Police Department (AL) 33 1,567 21.1 0.4 -- Cherokee Nation Marshal Service (OK) 32 197,684 0.2 6,702 0.1 Choctaw Nation Tribal Police Department (OK) 32 99,371 0.3 10,613 0.1 Colville Tribal Police Department (WA) 32 5,052 6.3 2,117 0.4 Saginaw Chippewa Tribal Police Department (MI) 30 1,799 16.7 218 3.4 Tulalip Tribal Police Services (WA) 30 2,869 10.5 35 21.4 Warm Springs Tribal Police Department (OR) 30 4,079 7.4 1,011 0.7 White Mountain Apache Police Department (AZ) 30 12,213 2.5 2,628 0.3 Isleta Police Department (NM) 29 3,980 7.3 331 2.2 Yakama Nation Tribal Police Department (WA) 28 16,815 1.7 2,153 0.3 Pascua Yaqui Tribal Police Department (AZ) 27 14,787 1.8 2 -- Puyallup Tribal Police Department (WA) 27 24,016 1.1 29 23.3 Rosebud Sioux Tribal Police Department (SD) 27 22,293 1.2 1,388 0.5 Red Lake Tribal Police Department (MN) 26 10,338 2.5 880 0.7 Oneida Indian Nation Police (NY) 25 650 38.5 0.1 -- Note: Land area data are from the U.S. Census Bureau, and include reservation land only. --Reservation land area is less than 25 square miles. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201118 Tribal law enforcement agencies were responsible for a broad range of services and functions during 2008 Nearly all general purpose tribal police departments were responsible for traditional law enforcement functions, such as routine patrol (100%), responding to citizen requests for service (100%), special events and crowd control (98%), criminal investigation (96%), and traffic enforcement (96%) (figure 2.2). About 4 in 5 departments were responsible for parking enforcement (80%), and about 2 in 3 departments dispatched calls for service (66%). About 3 in 5 general purpose tribal police departments had full-time community policing officers A majority of tribal police departments used a community policing approach in their efforts to prevent crime and maintain partnerships with the communities they serve. About three-fifths (59%) of departments had full-time sworn personnel serving as community policing officers (table 2.3). As of September 2008, about 500 tribal police officers were designated as community policing officers. In 2000, 73% of tribal agencies reported using community policing officers, with about 700 designated as such. For more than a third (36%) of tribal police departments, community policing efforts extended into the schools, with 82 full-time sworn personnel assigned as school resource officers. Although the percentage of departments using school resource officers in 2008 was about the same as in 2000 (37%), the total number of officers was about half of 2000 levels. Nearly all tribal police departments performed a variety of court-related functions In addition to law enforcement duties, nearly all tribal police departments were responsible for a variety of court-related functions (figure 2.3). The most common functions were executing arrest warrants (95%), enforcing protection orders (92%), serving process (89%), apprehending fugitives (88%), and providing court security (75%). Table 2.3 Use of community policing and school resource officers by tribal police departments, 2000 and 2008 2000 2008 Community policing officers Percent of agencies using 73% 59% Number of officers 714 503 School resource officers Percent of agencies using 37% 36% Number of officers 162 82 0 20 40 60 80 100 Percent of agencies Dispatching calls Parking enforcement Accident investigation Crime investigation Tra�c law enforcement Special events/crowd control Responding to calls for service Routine patrol Type of function Figure 2.2 Selected law enforcement functions performed by tribal police departments, 2008 Figure 2.3 Selected court-related functions performed by tribal police departments, 2008 0 20 40 60 80 100 Percent of agencies Type of function Enforcing child support orders Serving eviction notices Inmate transport Court security Apprehension of fugitives Serving process Enforcing protection orders Executing arrest warrants Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 19 Nearly half of tribal police departments were responsible for search and rescue operations Nearly 9 in 10 tribal police departments performed one or more special public safety functions, the most common being emergency management (65%) and animal control (64%) (figure 2.4). About a third (31%) provided emergency medical services. Nearly a fifth provided fire services (19%) and school crossing services (18%). More than half (58%) of tribal police departments performed at least one specialized function, such as search and rescue (43%), tactical operations (26%), or underwater recovery (10%). About 1 in 6 agencies operated at least one jail (17%), and about 1 in 10 agencies operated an overnight lockup facility separate from a jail (10%). (For more information, see Jails in Indian County, 2009, BJS Web, February 2011.) The 21 special jurisdiction agencies, whose primary focus was the enforcement of natural resources laws, performed a variety of functions as well. In addition to providing patrol and response services, a majority of these agencies performed the following functions: criminal investigation (82%), search and rescue (71%), apprehension of fugitives (59%), animal control (59%), traffic enforcement (59%), and dispatching calls for service (53%) (not shown in figure). About two-thirds of general purpose tribal police departments participated in a multiagency drug task force About 4 in 5 (78%) tribal police departments partnered with federal, state, and local agencies in multiagency task forces to combat crime problems in Indian country during 2008. These task forces allow participating agencies to share in pooled resources, information, and expertise across jurisdictional boundaries. Tribal police departments were most likely to participate in task forces formed to combat drug trafficking (66% of agencies) (figure 2.5). About 2 in 5 (41%) departments participated in multiagency gang task forces, and about a third (32%) participated in violent crime task forces. Smaller percentages of tribal police departments participated in anti- terrorism (17%) or human trafficking (9%) task forces. 0 20 40 60 80 Percent of agencies Jail operation School crossing services Fire services Tactical operations (SWAT) Emergency medical services Search and rescue Animal control Emergency management Type of function Figure 2.4 Selected special functions performed by tribal police departments, 2008 0 20 40 60 80 Percent of agencies Human tra�cking Anti- terrorism Violent crime GangsDrug tra�cking One or more types Type of function Figure 2.5 Task force participation of tribal police departments, 2008 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201120 Methodology The Bureau of Justice Statistics’ (BJS) Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies (CSLLEA) is conducted every 4 years to provide a complete enumeration of agencies and their employees. Employment data are reported for sworn and nonsworn personnel and, within these categories, by full-time or part- time status. Agencies also complete a checklist of functions they regularly perform, or for which they have primary responsibility. The CSLLEA provides national data on the number of state and local law enforcement agencies and employees for general purpose local police departments (including tribal agencies), sheriffs’ offices, the primary state law enforcement agencies, and special jurisdiction (e.g., natural resources) agencies. It also serves as the sampling frame for BJS surveys of law enforcement agencies. The 2008 CSLLEA form was mailed to approximately 20,000 agencies that were determined to potentially be operating on the reference date of September 30, 2008. This master list was created by compiling information from the following sources: � the 2004 CSLLEA � lists provided by Peace Officer Standards and Training offices, and other state agencies � an FBI list of agencies requesting new identifiers since the 2004 CSLLEA. Responding agencies were screened for eligibility and were excluded if any of the following conditions existed on the CSLLEA reference date of September 30, 2008: � The agency employed only part-time officers, and the total combined hours worked for these officers averaged less than 35 hours per week. � The agency contracted or outsourced to another agency for performance of all services. � The agency was closed, a duplicate listing, or otherwise an invalid entry on the master list. � The agency did not employ personnel with general arrest powers. � The agency did not operate with funds from a state, local, special district, or tribal government. � All sworn officers volunteered their time on an unpaid basis. Data on number and type of personnel were obtained from all eligible tribal agencies. For general purpose tribal police departments, the item response rates were as follows: community policing and school resource officers, 100%; agency functions, 99%; task force participation, 99%; and operating budget, 87%. References American Indians and Crime, NCJ 173386, BJS Web, February 1999. American Indian Population and Labor Force Report, 2005, U.S. Department of the Interior, Bureau of Indian Affairs, Office of Indian Services. Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies, 2008, NCJ 233982, BJS Web, June 2011. Census of Tribal Justice Agencies in Indian Country, 2002, NCJ 205332, BJS Web, December 2005. Indian Country Law Enforcement Review, U.S. Department of Justice, December 1999. Jails in Indian Country, 2009, NCJ 232223, BJS Web, February 2011. Local Police Departments, 2007, NCJ 231174, BJS Web, December 2010. Policing on American Indian Reservations, U.S. Department of Justice, National Institute of Justice, NCJ 186185, September 2001. Tribal Law Enforcement, 2000, NCJ 197936, BJS Web, January 2003. State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 21 State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 Steven W. Perry, Ron Malega, Ph.D., and Duren Banks, Ph.D., BJS Statisticians In 2007, 93 state court prosecutors’ offices reported jurisdiction under Public Law 83-280 (P.L. 280) for felonies committed in Indian country. Seventy-three percent of these offices prosecuted at least one felony case that arose from Indian country in 2007, including at least one offense that involved drugs (63%), domestic violence (60%), or aggravated assault (58%). This report presents selected findings from the Bureau of Justice Statistics’s (BJS) 2007 National Census of State Prosecutors. Criminal jurisdiction in Indian country is divided among federal, state, and tribal governments. Jurisdiction in a specific incident depends on the nature of the offense, whether the offender or victim was a tribal member, and the state in which the crime occurred. Crimes committed in Indian country are often subject to concurrent jurisdiction between multiple criminal justice agencies. The Major Crimes Act (18 U.S.C. § 1153), as amended, grants concurrent federal jurisdiction for 16 major crimes committed by Native Americans occurring in Indian country. State jurisdiction for crimes committed in Indian country is primarily provided for under P.L. 280. Tribal courts maintain concurrent jurisdiction when federal or state jurisdiction is applied. State prosecutors’ offices generally do not have jurisdiction over crimes committed in Indian country due to the sovereign status of federally recognized tribes in the United States. However, state prosecutors’ offices in 16 states may exercise jurisdiction over crimes committed on tribal lands under P.L. 280. This law established state jurisdiction over offenses committed by or against American Indians in Indian country, including federally recognized reservations, tribal communities, and identified trust lands. P.L. 280 is mandatory for 6 states and optional for 10 states. Highlights � Ninety-three state court prosecutors’ offices in the 16 P.L. 280 states reported jurisdiction for felonies committed in Indian country under P.L. 280. � Seventy-three percent of offices with jurisdiction in Indian country reported prosecuting at least one felony case committed in Indian country. � Most offices in P.L. 280 states prosecuted at least one offense involving drugs (63%), domestic violence (60%), or aggravated assault (58%). � Eighteen offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states with jurisdiction for Indian country prosecuted at least one rape, and 12 offices prosecuted a homicide. � Of state prosecutors’ offices that reported jurisdiction for felony cases in Indian country under P.L. 280, 70% served judicial districts with populations of less than 100,000 residents. � Offices with jurisdiction for felony crimes committed in Indian country had an average operating budget of $5.2 million in 2007. Criminal jurisdic tion in I ndian countr y Tribal jurisdiction � Crimes committed by Native Americans in Indian country. Sentences are limited to a maximum 3-year sentence of incarceration per count and 9 years per case (124 U.S.C. 2258 § 234 (a) (b)). Federal jurisdiction � Pursuant to the Major Crimes Act of 1885. 18 U.S.C. § 1153 and subsequent amendments State jurisdiction � All crimes on tribal lands specified under Public Law 83-280. 18 U.S.C. § 1162 � Crimes committed on tribal lands in which neither the victim nor the offender is a tribal member. Note: Criminal jurisdiction in Indian country depends on several factors, including the identity of the defendant, victim, type of offense, and where the crime was committed. U.S. Department of Justice Office of Justice Programs Bureau of Justice Statistics June 2011, NCJ 234241 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201122 According to the 2002 Census of Tribal Justice Agencies, 94 of the 123 responding tribes in mandatory P.L. 280 states relied on state courts. The 2002 Census was limited to American Indian tribes in the lower 48 states, so tribes in Alaska were excluded. The Census also found that 19 of 90 reporting tribes in optional P.L. 280 states relied on state courts (table 3.1). The federal government retains criminal jurisdiction for major crimes committed in Indian country in the remaining states where P.L. 280 does not apply. States retain jurisdiction for non-Indian crimes (those in which neither the offender nor the victim is a tribal member) committed in Indian country.* In 2007, 1,548 state court prosecutors’ offices were in states not affected by P.L. 280 and were excluded from this report. The 93 state prosecutors’ offices reporting jurisdiction under P.L. 280 in mandatory and optional states represent 14% of all state prosecutors’ offices in states affected by P.L. 280. Nearly all of these served districts that overlapped with or were adjacent to tribal lands (figure 3.1). Approximately a fifth of state prosecutors in mandatory P.L. 280 states reported jurisdiction for crimes committed in Indian country P.L. 280 gave select states legal jurisdiction over tribal members to prosecute crimes occurring on the reservation under existing state laws. These mandatory P.L. 280 states include California, Minnesota (except the Red Lake Reservation), Nebraska, Oregon (except the Warm Springs Reservation), Wisconsin, and Alaska (table 3.2). *Some tribes have been affected by states that have received a federal mandate to exercise jurisdiction outside of P.L. 280, e.g., through state-wide enactments, restoration acts, or land claims settlement acts (Tribal Court Clearinghouse, 2010, www.tribal-institute.org/ lists/jurisdiction.htm). Table 3.1 Number of tribes participating in the Census of Tribal Justice Agencies in Indian Country, by P.L. 280 status, type of court systems, and state, 2002 Number of tribes using— Participating in census Tribal justice systems Indigenous courts CFR courtsa Tribal courts Relying on state courtsb Mandatory states 123 39 8 9 37 94 California 88 7 2 7 7 74 Minnesota 12 12 3 0 12 4 Nebraska 4 3 0 2 3 2 Oregon 8 8 1 0 8 6 Wisconsin 11 9 2 0 7 8 Optional states 90 80 13 11 74 19 Arizona 17 16 3 0 16 0 Florida 1 0 0 0 0 1 Idaho 4 4 1 0 4 1 Iowa 1 0 0 0 0 1 Montana 6 6 1 0 5 0 Nevada 16 14 1 4 13 6 North Dakota 3 3 0 0 3 0 South Dakota 9 9 0 2 9 0 Utah 4 2 0 2 2 2 Washington 29 26 7 3 22 8 Note: The 2002 Census of Tribal Justice Agencies was limited to American Indian tribes in the lower 48 states. Source: Table reproduced from Census of Tribal Justice Agencies in Indian Country, 2002, NCJ 205332, BJS Web, December 2005. aCourt of Federal Regulations (CFR) operated by the Bureau of Indian Affairs (BIA). bTribes that rely on state court for jusidical services (e.g., felony courts, court-ordered treatment, and child support enforcement). Table 3.2 State prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction for crimes committed in Indian country, by P.L. 280 status and state, 2007 Number of offices— All prosecutors’ offices in P.L. 280 states* With jurisdiction for felony cases occurring in Indian country under P.L. 280 Prosecuting at least one felony case All P.L. 280 states 672 93 68 Mandatory states 294 56 47 Alaska 1 1 -- California 48 23 21 Minnesota 76 15 15 Nebraska 81 3 1 Oregon 31 7 4 Wisconsin 57 7 6 Optional states 378 37 21 Arizona 11 1 1 Florida 16 1 1 Idaho 34 6 4 Iowa 93 1 1 Montana 46 5 1 Nevada 15 2 0 North Dakota 43 2 1 South Dakota 58 1 1 Utah 26 3 2 Washington 36 15 9 Note: The 2007 Census of State Court Prosecutors included 2,330 offices, 66% (1,548) of which were located in states not affected by P.L. 280, and therefore were excluded from all analyses. --No information reported. *Excludes data missing for 110 offices. 23 M an da to ry P .L . 2 80 st at es Op tio na l P .L . 2 80 st at es In di an re se rv at io n (U .S . C en su s B ur ea u) Pr os ec ut or s’ o� ce s r ep or tin g ju ris di ct io n in In di an Co un try u nd er P .L . 2 80 Fi g u r e 3 .1 St at e p ro se cu to rs ’ o ffi ce s re p o rt in g ju ri sd ic ti o n in In d ia n c o u n tr y u n d er P .L . 2 80 , 2 00 7 N ot e: P ro se cu to rs ’ o ffi ce s i n no n- P.L . 2 80 st at es a re n ot sh ow n. So ur ce : B ur ea u of Ju st ic e St at ist ic s Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201124 In 2007, 19% of all state prosecutors’ offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states reported jurisdiction for felony cases occurring in Indian country. P.L. 280 permitted other states to acquire either complete or partial jurisdiction over crimes committed in Indian country at their option: Arizona, Florida, Idaho, Iowa, Montana, Nevada, North Dakota, South Dakota, Utah, and Washington. Ten percent of all prosecutors’ offices in optional P.L. 280 states reported jurisdiction for felony cases in Indian country in 2007. About three-quarters of offices with P.L. 280 jurisdiction prosecuted a felony case from Indian country in 2007 Sixty-eight of the 93 prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction in Indian country reported prosecuting at least one felony case committed in Indian country in 2007. Forty-seven offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states reported prosecuting at least one offense committed in Indian country, and 21 offices in optional P.L. 280 states reported prosecuting at least one offense committed in Indian country in 2007. Most offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states with jurisdiction for felony offenses in Indian country also reported prosecuting at least one drug-related crime (42 of 56 offices), domestic violence offense (40), aggravated assault (38), parole or probation violation (31), or a crime involving sexual assault or sexual abuse (30) (figure 3.2). Offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states with jurisdiction for Indian country also reported prosecuting serious felony offenses, including 18 offices that prosecuted at least one rape committed in Indian country and 12 offices that prosecuted a homicide. Prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction in Indian country had an average of 16 assistant prosecutors on staff The 2007 National Census of State Prosecutors collected operational and administrative information from state prosecutors’ offices, including budgets, staffing, and caseload. Offices reporting jurisdiction for crimes committed under P.L. 280 were not asked to disaggregate office resources or operations by whether they were directed toward crimes committed in Indian country or elsewhere in the judicial district. The census asked respondents to provide or estimate the total number of felony cases closed in 2007. The survey did not ask respondents to provide information on the number of cases that arose from crimes committed in Indian country. This section describes the entire operations of the state prosecutors’ offices reporting jurisdiction under P.L. 280, not operations specific to crimes committed in Indian country. Homicide Rape Robbery Sexual assault/abuse Parole/probation violation Aggravated assault Domestic violence Drug-related All felony cases prosecuted in Indian Country, under P.L. 280 Optional P.L. 280 Mandatory P.L. 280 Number of o�ces 47 21 42 17 40 16 38 16 31 15 30 10 21 8 18 5 12 4 Figure 3.2 State prosecutors’ offices reporting prosecution of specific crimes in Indian country, by P.L. 280 status, 2007 State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 25 Most (71) state prosecutors’ offices that reported jurisdiction for felony cases occurring in Indian country under P.L. 280 served judicial districts with populations of less than 100,000 residents or were part-time offices. In mandatory P.L. 280 states, 7 of the 56 offices with jurisdiction in Indian country served districts with 250,000 or more residents (table 3.3). Offices with jurisdiction for felony crimes committed in Indian country had an average 2007 budget of $5.2 million, or an expenditure of about $31 per district resident. The median budget was $722,000. The office staff included an average of 16 assistant prosecutors, 3 victim advocates, 4 legal services staff, and 19 support staff (table 3.4). Offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states reported an average of 61 total staff, including 19 assistant prosecutors, 8 investigators, and 22 support staff. Offices in optional P.L. 280 states reported an average of 38 total staff, 11 assistant prosecutors, 1 investigator, and 14 support staff. Offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states, reported closing a similar number of felony cases in 2007 compared to optional state offices. State prosecutors’ offices in optional P.L. 280 states closed 1,784 felony cases in 2007, while offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states closed 1,699 felony cases. Table 3.3 Type of state prosecutors’ offices reporting jurisdiction in Indian country, by P.L. 280 status, 2007 Total P.L. 280 Status Population served Mandatory Optional All offices 93 56 37 Full-time offices serving a judicial district with— 1 million or more residents 4 2 2 250,000 to 999,999 5 5 0 100,000 to 249,999 13 8 5 99,999 or fewer 65 37 28 Part-time offices* 6 4 2 *Part-time offices are defined as those that reported a part-time chief prosecutor in 2007. Table 3.4 Budget, staffing, and caseload of state prosecutors’ offices, by P.L. 280 status, 2007 Total P.L. 280 status Mandatory Optional Mean Median Mean Median Mean Median Total resident population served 156,495 28,893 177,407 28,965 124,846 28,606 Total operating budget $5,173,831 $722,208 $6,560,838 $735,735 $3,074,577 $670,000 Budget per resident population served $31 $26 $35 $27 $25 $24 Total staffa 51 12 61 12 38 12 Chief prosecutor 1 1 1 1 1 1 Assistant prosecutors 16 3 19 4 11 3 Civil prosecutors 2 0 1 0 4 1 Supervisors 2 1 2 0 2 1 Managers 1 0 1 0 0 0 Victim advocates 3 1 3 1 2 1 Legal services 4 0 3 0 4 1 Investigators 5 0 8 0 1 0 Support staff 19 3 22 4 14 3 Felony cases closedb 1,733 300 1,699 300 1,784 275 Note: Statistics include imputed data for some offices. Data were missing for 3 offices that did not provide total operating budget, 1 office that did not provide staffing information, and 6 offices that did not provide the number of felony cases closed. See Methodology for more information. aAll staff statistics are presented as full-time equivalent staff, calculated as the number of full-time staff plus 50% of the number of half time staff. bIncludes all cases charged as a felony that had a judgment of conviction, acquittal, or dismissal, with or without prejudice, entered by the court. Cases closed include all felony cases closed by the prosecutors’ offices and include an unknown number of cases committed in Indian country. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201126 Methodology The 2007 National Census of State Court Prosecutors (NCSP-07) surveyed 2,330 chief prosecutors in the United States who handled felony cases in state courts of general jurisdiction. The census did not include municipal attorneys or county attorneys who primarily operate in courts of limited jurisdiction. This report describes characteristics of offices that reported jurisdiction for crimes committed in Indian country under P.L. 280 in 2007. Most (66%) state court prosecutors’ offices included in the 2007 census were in states not affected by P.L. 280 and are excluded from this report. The operational and administrative characteristics described in this report represent the functions of the entire office and are not restricted to those functions, staff, budget, or other resources specifically devoted to crimes committed in Indian country, unless otherwise noted. Data Imputations BJS relied on previously reported data and valid office characteristics to impute values for critical variables where missing. These critical variables, found in Table 3.4, include the total operating budget, total staff, full- or part-time status of chief prosecutor, number of assistant prosecutors, and number of felony cases closed. Critical variables that were missing in 2007 were imputed from the same office’s response to the 2001 Census of State Prosecutors wherever possible. For each jurisdiction with valid 2001 and 2007 data, an adjustment ratio was calculated as the ratio of the critical variable’s 2001 value to its 2007 value. All ratios greater than the 90th percentile were discarded for imputation purposes. For those offices missing 2007 data, a hot deck imputation procedure was employed to impute the adjustment ratio value from the office’s nearest neighbor in terms of state and population size. Where there were no suitable donors in the same state, a donor of similar population size was used. The 2001 data were then adjusted using the imputed adjustment ratio to create the imputed 2007 value for the critical variable where missing. This procedure was followed for 3 offices missing total operating budget, 1 office missing staffing information, and 6 offices missing the number of felony cases closed. Reference Census of Tribal Justice Agencies in Indian Country, 2002, NCJ 205332, BJS Web, `December 2005. Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 27 Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 Todd D. Minton, BJS Statistician At midyear 2009, a total of 2,176 inmates were confined in Indian country jails, a 1.9% increase from the 2,135 inmates confined at midyear 2008 (figure 4.1). This count was based on data from 80 facilities, including jails, confinement facilities, detention centers, and other correctional facilities, that were in operation in Indian country at midyear 2009. For 2008, the number of inmates was based on data for 82 facilities in operation at midyear 2008. The number of inmates held in Indian country jails between 2004 and 2009 increased by 25% from 1,745 inmates to 2,176. The number of jails in Indian country has increased between 2004 and 2009 The Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS) collected data from 68 correctional facilities in Indian country in 2004, from 79 in 2007, 82 in 2008, and 80 in 2009. The survey was not conducted in 2005 and 2006. Over the 5-year period, a number of facilities closed and new facilities became operational. Eleven facilities permanently closed between 2004 and 2009, and a total of 21 facilities were newly Highlights � The number of inmates confined in Indian country jails increased by 1.9% between midyear 2008 and 2009, reaching 2,176 inmates. � Between June 2008 and June 2009, the average daily jail population in Indian country increased by 12%, and the percentage of occupied bed space increased from 64.2% to 73.5%. � Eleven jails (14% of all facilities) held 51% of inmates confined at midyear 2009. � During June 2009, the number of inmates admitted to Indian country jails (11,357) was about 5 times the size of the average daily population (2,124). � The expected average length of stay increased by a half day from 5.1 days during June 2008 to 5.6 days during June 2009. � Indian country jail authorities reported no deaths in custody between July 1, 2008, and June 30, 2009, down from 4 reported deaths during the 12-month period ending June 30, 2008. � Attempted suicides by inmates declined from 78 in 2008 to 56 in 2009. � Indian country jails held fewer inmates for domestic violence at midyear 2009 (252), continuing the downward trend in the number held for this offense since 2007 (362). � The percentage of certified correctional officers working in Indian country jails increased steadily, from 63% at midyear 2007 to 79% at midyear 2009. U.S. Department of Justice Office of Justice Programs Bureau of Justice Statistics June 2011, NCJ 232223 0 400 800 1,200 1,600 2,000 2,400 Number of inmates 20092008200720042003200220012000 At midyear Figure 4.1 Inmates confined in Indian country jails, midyear 2000-2004 and 2007-2009 Note: The Survey of Jails in Indian Country was not conducted in 2005 and 2006. Midyear count is the number of inmates held on the last weekday in June. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201128 constructed. BJS estimated inmate population counts for 7 facilities in 2004 and 4 facilities in 2007 that did not respond to the surveys. All known operating facilities responded to the 2008 and 2009 surveys. (See Methodology for additional details on facility counts and participation in the surveys.) (See Methodology in Jails in Indian Country, 2009, NCJ 232223, BJS Web, February 2010, for additional details on facility counts and participation in the surveys.) On an average day in June, the percentage of occupied bed space increased from 64.2% to 73.5% At midyear 2009, the 80 jail facilities in Indian country were rated to hold 2,891 inmates, down from 2,963 in 82 facilities during the same period in 2008 (table 4.1). The average daily population (ADP) in June—the population measure used to calculate percent of capacity occupied—increased by nearly 12%, from 1,903 inmates (June 2008) to 2,124 (June 2009), while the capacity to hold inmates decreased by 2%. Consequently, the percentage of rated capacity occupied in Indian country jails increased from 64% to 73% during the period. On June 30, 2009, the 80 facilities held a total of 2,176 inmates and were operating at 75% of rated capacity, remaining relatively stable since 2007. From June 2004 to June 2009, the overall number of beds (or rated capacity) grew at a faster rate (34%) than the the inmate population (25%). Small number of jails held more than half of the inmate population Eleven jails held more than half (51%) of the total inmate population at midyear 2009 (table 4.2). Between midyear 2008 and midyear 2009, the population in these jails increased by 247 inmates (29%). In 2008, 9 of the 11 facilities held the majority of jail inmates in Indian country. Over the 365-day period, 6 jails that held the majority of inmates in Indian country in 2008 experienced large declines in their jail populations. The combined decrease in the size of the jail population in these facilities was 33% (90 inmates) from midyear 2008 to midyear 2009. Among the 11 facilities holding the majority of inmates in 2009, the Gila River Department of Rehabilitation and Supervision - Adult facility reported the largest decline (30 inmates or 17%) in the number of jail inmates. The jail population in this facility has decreased by 92 inmates (38%) from its peak of 241 inmates reported at midyear 2007. Table 4.1 Inmates, rated capacity, and percent of capacity occupied in Indian country jails, 2004 and 2007–2009 2004 2007 2008 2009 Number of inmates Midyeara 1,745 2,163 2,135 2,176 ADPb 1,622 2,046 1,903 2,124 Rated capacity 2,162 2,900 2,963 2,891 Percent of capacity occupiedc Midyear 80.7% 74.6% 72.1% 75.3% ADP 75.0 70.6 64.2 73.5 Number of operating facilities 68 79 82 80 aMidyear count is the number of inmates held on the last weekday in June. bAverage daily population (ADP) is the sum of the number of inmates held on each day in June, divided by 30. cPopulation as a percent of capacity occupied is calculated by dividing the population count of a facility by its rated capacity and multiplying by 100. Table 4.2 Jails in Indian country that held the majority of inmates in 2009 compared to 2008, by facility Custody population at midyear* Change in population Facility 2008 2009 Number Percent Total, 11 facilities 859 1,106 247 29% Tohono O’odham Adult Detention Center (AZ) 137 192 55 40% Gila River Department of Rehabilitation and Supervision - Adult (AZ) 179 149 -30 -17 San Carlos Department of Corrections and Rehabilitation - Adult and Juvenile Detention (AZ) 88 147 59 67 Truxton Canyon Adult Detention Center (AZ) 39 105 66 169 White Mountain Apache Detention Center (AZ) 101 95 -6 -6 Oglala Sioux Tribal Offenders Facility (SD) 52 95 43 83 Standing Rock Law Enforcement and Adult Detention Center (ND) 71 93 22 31 Nisqually Adult Corrections (WA) 59 73 14 24 Menominee Tribal Detention Facility (WI) 54 53 -1 -2 Navajo Department of Corrections - Shiprock Police Department and Adult Detention (NM) 46 52 6 13 Laguna Tribal Police and Detention Center (NM) 33 52 19 58 Note: Based on facilities that held the most inmates on June 30, 2009. *Midyear count is the number of inmates held on the last weekday in June. Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 29 Two facilities, the Truxton Canyon Adult Detention Center and the Laguna Tribal Police and Detention Center, were among the 11 facilities holding the majority of jail inmates in 2009. These 2 facilities were not among the 11 facilities holding the majority of inmates in 2008. (See Jails in Indian Country, 2008, BJS Web, December 2008.) The Truxton Canyon Adult Detention Center reported the largest increase in the inmate population (66 inmates or 169%) between midyear 2008 and midyear 2009. The Laguna Tribal Police and Detention Center increased by 58% (19 inmates) between 2008 and 2009. Based on the 80 facilities responding to the survey in both 2008 and 2009, the overall change in the inmate population (up 45 inmates) was relatively small. Thirty-three facilities, which were mostly the larger facilities, accounted for this increase (not shown in table). Change in the size of the jail population in Indian country was varied. More than half of the 80 jails experienced either a decline (40 jails) or no change (7 jails) in the size of their inmate population over the 12-month period ending midyear 2009. Overall, the 50% increase (415 inmates) in the jail population in 33 jails was offset by a 30% decline (370 inmates) in 40 jails. The use of jail space varied by facility size Indian country jails rated to hold 25 to 49 inmates were operating at 89% of their rated capacity on June 30, 2009, and at 79% on an average day in June. An average day in June was based on the ADP, or the sum of the numbers held on each day in June divided by 30. In contrast, the lowest percentage of capacity occupied during June 2009 was among the 11 small jails rated to hold fewer than 10 inmates. These facilities were operating at 21% of rated capacity at midyear and at 17% of capacity on an average day in June 2009 (figure 4.2). Compared to facilities in all other size categories, the large jails with a rated capacity of 50 or more inmates reported the only increase in occupied bed space between 2008 and 2009. The percentage of capacity occupied in these jails increased from 51% to 69% during the 12 months ending at midyear 2009, and from 49% to 73% on an average day in June 2008 and 2009. The amount of bed space occupied was also measured based on a facility’s most crowded day in June. Nearly half (38 facilities) of the 80 facilities in Indian country were operating above rated capacity on the most crowded day in June (table 4.3). Of those Table 4.3 Number of Indian country jails, by percent of rated capacity occupied, June 2009 Number of jails Percent of capacity occupieda Midyearb ADPc Peakd Less than 25% 17 20 7 25-49% 15 11 8 50-74% 19 21 15 75-100% 11 15 12 More than 100% 18 13 38 aPopulation as a percent of capacity occupied is calculated by dividing the population count of a facility by its rated capacity and multiplying by 100. bMidyear count is the number of inmates held on the last weekday in June. cAverage daily population (ADP) is the sum of the number of inmates held on each day in June, divided by 30. dPeak population is the population held on the day in June in which the custody population of a facility was the largest. 0 20 40 60 80 100 120 140 Peak 50 or more25 to 4910 to 24Fewer than 10 inmatesTotal Percent of capacity occupied ADP Midyear Figure 4.2 Rated capacity occupied, by type of inmate count, June 2009 Note: Rated capacity is the maximum number of beds or inmates assigned by a rating official. Midyear count is the number of inmates held on the last weekday in June. Average daily population (ADP) is the sum of the number of inmates held on each day in June divided by 30. Peak population is the population held on the day in June in which the custody population of a facility was the largest. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201130 facilities, 18 were operating above rated capacity on June 30, and 13 were operating above rated capacity on an average day during June 2009. High volumes of admissions of inmates were processed through Indian country jails Eighty Indian country jails admitted 11,357 persons during June 2009, up slightly from 11,149 admissions in 81 facilities during June 2008 (table 4.4). The number of admissions grew by 1.6% in the 79 facilities that reported data on admissions in both June 2009 (11,323) and June 2008 (11,147) (not shown in table). Admissions to facilities rated to hold between 25 to 49 inmates accounted for about 48% (5,503) of all admissions in June 2009, down from 59% of all admissions in June 2008. The largest Indian country jails accounted for less than 20% of all facilities and reported a total increase of nearly 75% in the number of jail admissions during the 12-month period. Admissions to the largest Indian country jails increased from 1,915 inmates to 3,342 from June 2008 to June 2009. The 15 jails rated to hold 50 or more inmates had the highest average number of admissions per month (233), compared to jails in all other size categories (not shown in table). Inmate deaths and attempted suicides in Indian country jails declined Indian country jail authorities reported no deaths in custody between July 1, 2008, and June 30, 2009, down from 4 reported deaths during the 12-month period ending June 30, 2008. Attempted suicides by inmates declined from 78 in 2008 to 56 in 2009. Expected length of stay was 5.6 days for Indian country jail inmates in June 2009 During June 2009, the expected average length of stay for inmates confined in Indian country jails was 5.6 days, up from 5.1 days during June 2008. Length of stay is the time held in custody from admission to release. The expected length of stay for inmates was the highest (9.1 days) Table 4.4 Admissions and expected length of stay in Indian country jails during June, by facility size, June 2009 Facility sizea Number of facilities ADPb Estimated June admissions Expected average length of stayc Total 80 2,124 11,357 5.6 days Fewer than 10 inmates 11 9 133 2.1 10 to 24 24 276 2,379 3.5 25 to 49 30 820 5,503 4.5 50 or more 15 1,018 3,342 9.1 Note: Detail may not sum to total due to rounding. aBased on the rated capacity, the maximum number of beds or inmates assigned by a rating official. bAverage daily population (ADP) is the sum of the number of inmates held on each day in June, divided by 30. cExpected length of stay was calculated by dividing the average daily population (ADP) by the number of June admissions, and multiplying by 30. See Methodology in Jails in Indian Country, 2009 for details on estimating expected length of stay. Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 31 Table 4.5 Number of inmates confined in Indian country jails, by demographic characteristic, conviction status, and offense, midyear 2002, 2004, and 2007–2009 Number of inmates held at midyeara Percent of inmates held at midyear Characteristic 2000 2002 2004 2007 2008 2009 2000 2002 2004 2007 2008 2009 Total 1,775 2,006 1,745 1,996 2,135 2,176 100% 100% 100% 100% 100% 100% Sex Male 1,421 1,618 1,346 1,582 1,678 1,754 80% 81% 77% 79% 79% 81% Female 354 388 398 414 457 422 20 19 23 21 21 19 Age group/sex Adults 1,498 1,699 1,546 1,743 1,882 1,919 84% 85% 89% 87% 88% 88% Male 1,214 1,399 1,222 1,415 1,498 1,571 68 70 70 71 70 72 Female 284 300 324 328 384 348 16 15 19 16 18 16 Juveniles 277 307 198 253 253 257 16 15 11 13 12 12 Male 207 219 124 167 180 183 12 11 7 8 8 8 Female 70 88 74 86 73 74 4 4 4 4 3 3 Conviction status Convicted 1,072 1,120 966 1,116 1,340 1,496 61% 57% 58% 59% 63% 69% Unconvicted 689 857 697 763 776 680 39 43 42 41 37 31 Type of offense Domestic violence ... 291 257 362 307 252 ...% 15% 18% 20% 15% 12% Assault ... ... 190 233 308 299 ... ... 13 13 15 15 Rape or sexual assault ... ... 34 45 42 42 ... ... 2 2 2 2 Other violence ... ... 79 108 177 168 ... ... 6 6 9 8 DWI/DUIb 274 226 195 137 184 229 17 11 14 8 9 11 Drug law violation 133 126 104 132 104 107 8 6 7 7 5 5 Other ... ... 569 804 954 955 ... ... 40 44 46 47 Offense not reported ... ... 317 175 59 124 / / / / / / Note: Detailed characteristics may not be equal to the total number of confined inmates because of incomplete data. See appendix tables 1-3 in Jails in Indian Country, 2009, NCJ 232223, BJS Web, February 2011, for a list of all facilities and inmate characteristics. aMidyear count is the number of inmates held on the last weekday in June. bIncludes driving while intoxicated and driving while under the influence of drugs or alcohol. ...Not collected. /Not reported. in facilities that were rated to hold 50 or more inmates, down from 10.3 days in June 2008. Inmates held in jails rated to hold less than 10 inmates experienced the shortest expected length of stay (2.1 days). Inmate characteristics remain relatively unchanged; the number held for domestic violence declined Inmate characteristics by sex, age, and offense have changed in absolute numbers since 2000 (table 4.5). However, the distribution within most categories remained stable between 2000 and 2008, with a change in the distribution of inmates by sex, conviction status, and offense type at midyear 2009. Adult males accounted for the largest portion of the inmate population in Indian country jails during the decade. The female jail population had small but steady increases from midyear 2000 to 2008, with a nearly 8% decrease in the size of this population between midyear 2008 and midyear 2009. Except for one juvenile female inmate, the decline was entirely among the adult female jail population. The percentage of convicted inmates increased from 57% in 2002 to 69% in 2009. Inmates confined for a violent offense made up about 37% of the jail population at midyear 2009, down from 41% at midyear 2008. Most (75%) of this decline was among the population held for domestic violence. Domestic violence (12%) and simple or aggravated assault (15%) accounted for the largest percentage of violent offenders held in 2009, followed by unspecified violent offenses (8%) and rape or sexual assault (2%). Since peaking at midyear 2007, the percentage of inmates held for domestic violence has steadily declined, from 20% in 2007 to 12% in 2009. The Gila River Department of Rehabilitation and Supervision - Adult accounted for a large portion of the decline in domestic violence offenders between 2007 and 2009. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201132 It reported a 38% decrease in the confined inmate population between midyear 2007 (241) and midyear 2009 (149), and a 74% decline in the number of inmates held for a domestic violence (from 180 inmates in 2007 to 46 in 2009). The number of certified correctional officers and in-service training steadily increased Seventy-nine Indian country jails employed 1,332 persons at midyear 2009 (table 4.6). About 69% (916) of all personnel were jail operations staff, including correctional officers and other staff who spent more than 50% of their time supervising inmates. The remaining 416 jail personnel included administrative employees, educational staff, technical or professional staff, clerical, maintenance, or food service staff, and other job functions. Overall, the ratio of inmates to jail operations employees was 2.4 inmates to 1 employee at midyear 2009, remaining relatively stable since 2008 (2.3 to 1) and 2004 (2.5 to 1). Seventy-six facilities reported that 710 (79%) correctional officers received basic detention officer certification, up from 69% in 2008 and 63% in 2007 (not shown). Seventy-four facilities reported that 750 (84%) correctional officers received 40 hours of in-service training, up from 74% in 2008 and 70% in 2007. Table 4.6 Persons employed in Indian country jails, by job function, midyear 2009 Job function Number Percent Totala 1,332 100% Administrativeb 136 10.2% Jail operations 916 68.8 Educational staff 29 2.2 Technical/professional 51 3.8 Clerical/maintenance/food service 173 13.0 Number of inmates per jail operations staff 2.4 aIncludes 27 other persons with unspecified functions not shown in table. bIncludes jail administrators, assistants, and other personnel who work in an administrative capacity more than 50% of the time. Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 33 Methodology The Annual Survey of Jails in Indian Country (SJIC) includes all known Indian country correctional facilities operated by tribal authorities or the Bureau of Indian Affairs (BIA), U.S. Department of the Interior. The survey was conducted in June 2009, and included the number of inmates and percent of capacity occupied based on the ADP, midyear population, and peak population in facilities in June 2009. (See table 10 in Jails in Indian Country, 2009, BJS Web, February 2011.) Through a cooperative agreement with the Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS), Westat, Inc. conducted the SJIC to describe all adult and juvenile jail facilities and detention centers in Indian country. For this report, Indian country includes reservations, pueblos, rancherias, and other appropriate areas (18 U.S.C.§ 1151). The reference date for the survey is June 30, 2009. Annually, BIA provides BJS a list of Indian country jail facilities, including detention centers, jails, and other correctional facilities operated by tribal authorities or BIA. BJS uses this list to update its existing roster of jails in Indian country. BJS obtains data from administrators of Indian country jails by mailed questionnaires and through follow-up phone calls and facsimiles. In 2004, BJS contacted administrators in 70 facilities to participate in the survey. BJS received responses from 61 facilities; 7 did not respond, and 2 facilities were non-operational. In 2007, the BJS roster consisted of 86 facilities. Seventy-nine of the facility administrators responded to the survey; 4 did not respond, and BJS found that 3 facilities were non- operational. In 2008, BJS’s roster of Indian country jails consisted of 85 facilities. BJS received responses from 82 facility administrators; there were no nonrespondents, and 3 facilities were non-operational. For 2009, the BJS roster consisted of 86 facilities. BJS received responses from 80 facility administrators; there were no nonrespondents, and 6 facilities were non-operational. For comparison over time, BJS estimated data on inmate populations for the 7 facilities in 2004 and 4 facilities in 2008 that did not respond to the surveys. Expected length of stay The stock-flow ratio method was used to measure the expected average length of stay for inmates held during June 2009 in the 80 Indian country jails that responded to stock and flow items in the survey: Stock—average daily population Flow—inmate admissions during June 2009 Stock-flow ratio in June 2009 (2,124/11,357=0.187) Expected length of stay in days (0.187 × 30)—is the average number of days held in custody from admission to release. Indian country is a statutory term that includes all lands within an Indian reservation, dependent Indian communities, and Indian trust allotments (18 U.S.C. § 1151). Courts interpret Section 1151 to include all lands held in trust for tribes or their members. (See United States v. Roberts, 185 F.3d 1125 (10th Cir. 1999).) Tribal authority to imprison American Indian offenders is limited to one year per offense by statute (25 U.S.C. § 1302), a $5,000 fine, or both. Tribal law enforcement agencies act as first responders to both felony and misdemeanor crimes. For most of Indian country, the federal government provides felony law enforcement concerning crimes by or against Indians. Certain areas of Indian country are under Public Law 83-280, as amended. P.L. 280 conferred jurisdiction on certain states over Indian country and suspended enforcement of the Major Crimes Act (18 U.S.C. § 1153) and the General Crimes Act (18 U.S.C. § 1152) in those areas. Indian tribes retain concurrent jurisdiction to enforce laws in Indian country where P.L. 280 applies. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201134 Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 35 Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System Mark Motivans, Ph.D., and Howard Snyder, Ph.D., BJS Statisticians The federal criminal justice response to tribal youth varies by the state in which the offense occurred, the nature of the offense, the availability of community- and confinement-based services, and discretionary decisions made by tribal, state, and federal justice agencies. Cases involving tribal youth in the federal system may result in 1) a delinquency adjudication and court-ordered supervision and out-of-home placement, or 2) the youth being transferred to adult status and prosecuted and sentenced as an adult. This summary describes the federal response to tribal youth during the case-processing stages from investigation to corrections. In this report, a federal juvenile delinquent is a person who has committed an offense while under age 18, and the federal prosecutor has certified a federal basis for jurisdiction. Juvenile and youth are used interchangeably in this report. The number of tribal youth in matters concluded by federal prosecutors and the total number of tribal youth prosecuted decreased from 2003 to 2008 (figure 5.1). Tribal youth in matters concluded by federal prosecutors dropped to 115 in 2008, down from 230 in 2003. Highlights � In 2008, relatively few juveniles were referred to federal prosecutors (315 out of 178,570 suspects) or admitted to federal prison jurisdiction (156 out 71,663 offenders). � Tribal youth (70) comprised nearly half of juveniles (152) handled by the federal courts in 2008. � Federal judicial districts of Arizona, Montana, South Dakota, New Mexico, and North Dakota accounted for 94% of tribal youth investigated, 92% of those prosecuted, and 88% of those admitted to federal prison jurisdiction in 2008. � In 2008, about 72% of tribal youth were investigated for violent offenses, including sexual abuse (35%), assault (20%), and murder (17%). � About 40% of matters involving tribal youth were declined by federal prosecutors in 2008. � A greater share of cases involving tribal youth in U.S. district courts were terminated by conviction (91%) than by dismissal (9%). � From 1994 to 2008, the lowest number of tribal (72) and non-tribal youth (84) admitted to the jurisdiction of federal prison authorities occurred in 2008. � Admissions to federal prison jurisdiction among tribal youth declined 10% per year from 1999 to 2008, while non-tribal youth admissions declined 12% per year. � In 2008, tribal youth served an average of 26 months under federal jurisdiction, which was more than double the tribal justice system maximum sentence of 12 months. U.S. Department of Justice Office of Justice Programs Bureau of Justice Statistics June 2011, NCJ 234218 Findings presented in this report are mostly from a recent study conducted by The Urban Institute under a cooperative agreement with the Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS). The study was also sponsored by the Office of Juvenile Justice and Delinquency Prevention (OJJDP). See page 43 for more information. Figure 5.1 Tribal youth in matters concluded and in matters prosecuted by U.S. attorneys, 2000–2008 Number of tribal youth Fiscal year 0 50 100 150 200 250 Suspects in matters prosecuted Suspects in matters concluded 200820072006200520042003200220012000 Source: Urban Institute analysis. See Methodology for more information. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201136 Tracking tribal youth through the stages of the federal criminal case process The federal criminal justice system is not currently well- equipped to monitor how tribal juvenile offenders are processed across stages. There is a lack of unified, system-wide data standards in reporting how youth— especially tribal youth—are handled in the federal system. Juveniles or offenses committed in Indian country are not systematically tracked across the federal justice agencies. Researchers have to devise analytic methods to identify tribal youth using administrative data from each criminal justice stage (arrest, sentencing, and corrections). How is federal jurisdic tion over tribal juvenile delinquents determined? The determination of jurisdiction over offenses occurring in Indian country is first subject to whether state courts have jurisdiction based on Public Law 280 (P.L. 280).1 If a state has P. L. 280 status, jurisdiction over offenses occurring in Indian country lies with the state or tribal courts, not the federal courts. The determination of whether federal jurisdiction applies next depends on the offender and victim in the crime: � If the offender is a juvenile tribal member and the victim is also a tribal member, and the offense is 1 of 15 crimes covered by the Major Crimes Act then jurisdiction is with both the tribal and federal courts.2 � If the offender is a juvenile tribal member and the victim is a non-tribal member, and the crime is covered by the Major Crimes Act or federal enclave status, then federal and tribal courts have shared jurisdiction. The Assimilative Crimes Act permits state law to be applied in federal court where the Major Crimes Act does not apply but federal interest exists. � If the crime involves a non-tribal offender and a tribal member victim, then federal courts have exclusive jurisdiction. Once federal jurisdiction has been established, the Federal Juvenile Delinquency Act (FJDA) provides the procedures to bring the tribal youth to federal court. A federal juvenile delinquent is defined as a person who has committed an offense while less than 18 years old, but has not reached age 21 at sentencing. Juvenile and youth are used interchangeably in this report. How are juveniles handled in the federal justice system? Most juveniles, or persons under age 18, in the United States are handled in state or local courts, which have a separate juvenile justice system, rather than in the federal courts. Federal law permits handling of juveniles in the federal system only in limited circumstances. Apart from those committing crimes in Indian country or on military bases, juveniles that commit offenses as members of drug trafficking gangs, violent criminal gangs, or other federal offenses may be subject to federal jurisdiction. In these cases, the U.S. attorney for each district must certify to the district court that (1) the juvenile court or court of a state does not have jurisdiction or refuses to assume jurisdiction; 2) the state does not have available programs or services adequate for the needs of juveniles; or 3) the offense charged is a felony crime of violence or specified drug offenses, and there is substantial federal interest in the case. I n what circumstances are tribal and non- tribal juveniles transferred to adult status (for prosecution and sentencing as an adult rather than a juvenile delinquent)? Once federal jurisdiction has been determined and certification of delinquency established, a transfer hearing establishes the status of juveniles as to whether they will be transferred for prosecution as an adult. Felony crimes of violence or drug or firearm offenses trigger eligibility for adult transfer with certain age restrictions. Age thirteen is the minimum age for transfer to adult status for murder and assault, and for robbery, bank robbery, or aggravated sexual abuse with a firearm. An exception is crimes committed in Indian country where the tribe has opted not to permit prosecution of juveniles age 13 as adults. Age fifteen is the minimum age for transfer to adult status for committing any crime of violence (including physical force against a person or property). A juvenile can be housed in a Federal Bureau of Prisons (BOP) institution at age 18 if sentenced as an adult. BOP does not operate its own facilities for juveniles; rather, they contract with private entities and state and local governments for both secure and non-secure (community- based) juvenile facilities to house tribal and non-tribal youth under their jurisdiction. 1Congress passed Public Law 280 in 1953, which relinquishes the federal government of criminal and civil jurisdiction in certain states and places jurisdiction with those states. 2The Major Crimes Act provides federal jurisdiction over certain offenses committed by tribal members. (See Title 18 U.S.C. §§ 1152, 1153.) Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 37 Table 5.1 Reason for matters declined for prosecution with tribal youth suspects, 2005–2008 Reasons for declinations Fiscal year Matters concluded Number of declinations Case- relateda Suspect- relatedb No crime Referred to other authoritiesc OtherTotal 2005 172 69 100% 58% 10% 9% 13% 10% 2006 164 80 100% 61 10 10 13 6 2007 143 68 100% 47 15 10 18 10 2008 115 46 100% 50 7 15 20 8 aIncludes weak evidence, stale case, witness problems, or jurisdiction or venue problems. bIncludes age of offender and offender ‘s criminal history and drug/alcohol use. cIncludes pretrial alternative resolutions, such as pretrial diversion. Source: Urban Institute analysis of Executive Office for U.S. Attorneys, National LIONS data base, fiscal years 2005–2008. Investigation and Prosecution Tribal police are often the first to respond to a crime in Indian country. Offenses committed by tribal youth may be investigated by a combination of tribal police and federal law enforcement agencies. The federal Bureau of Investigation (FBI) and the Bureau of Indian Affairs (BIA) are the primary federal law enforcement agencies investigating tribal youth matters. Tribal youth commonly enter the federal justice system with an arrest for a warrant issued on either a complaint or juvenile information (written accusation made by the prosecutor). For serious offenses that may indicate a federal crime, the U.S. attorney’s office in the district is notified as is the juvenile’s parent/guardian. The juvenile must be taken before a U.S. magistrate as soon as possible, where charges are read and the juvenile is informed of rights. Federal prosecutors next determine if the matter should be adjudicated in federal courts, disposed by U.S. magistrate, or declined for prosecution. In 2008, 4 in 10 matters involving a tribal youth were declined by federal prosecutors During 2008, 40% of tribal youth in matters concluded were declined for further prosecution, which was lower than the 46% declination rate for non-tribal youth in 2008. However, the average declination rate for tribal youth (45%) was higher than for non- tribal youth (37%) from 2004 to 2008. The most common reason for declination of tribal youth matters in 2008 was case related (50%) (table 5.1). Case-related reasons included weak evidence, stale case, witness problems, and jurisdiction or venue problems (figure 5.2). Some declined matters involved tribal youth that were subsequently referred to other authorities for prosecution, such as to the tribe or the state where the tribe is located. The share of declinations for tribal youth that were referred to other authorities or received an alternative resolution increased from 13% of all declinations in 2005 to 20% in 2008. Among non-tribal youth, the most common reason for declination (71%) was that the suspect was a juvenile (not shown in table). Most tribal youth in matters referred to U.S. attorneys were prosecuted by federal prosecutors In 2008, 59% of tribal youth who were referred to federal prosecutors were prosecuted, which was higher than the 54% prosecution rate for non-tribal youth in 2008 (including matters disposed by U.S. magistrates). From 2004 to 2008, the averageprosecution rate for tribal youth (55%) was comparable to that of non-tribal youth (53%). Various factors go into the decision to prosecute a matter, including seriousness of the crime, strength of the evidence, youth’s criminal history and drug/alcohol use, tribal capacity to prosecute, and tribal preference. Tribes having concurrent jurisdiction with federal jurisdiction may have limitations on available secure placement options and treatment resources. The potential penalty that could be received if a matter was handled in tribal or state venues may also be considered.3 3The Indian Civil Rights Act (Title 25 U.S.C. § 1302(7)), for example, limited tribes in sentencing persons convicted of serious crimes to a maximum of 1 year in jail and a $5,000 fine. Recently, the Tribal Law and Order Act extended the maximum sentence that a tribe can impose to three years. Figure 5.2 Case-related reasons for matters declined for prosecution with tribal youth suspects, 2005–2008 Jurisdiction or venue problems Stale case Witness problems Weak evidence Percent of cases 77% 13% 8% 2% Source: Urban Institute analysis of Executive Office for U.S. Attorneys, National LIONS data base, fiscal years 2005–2008. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201138 Nearly 9 of 10 tribal youth admitted to Federal Bureau of Prisons jurisdiction from 2006 to 2008 came from five federal judicial districts From 2006 to 2008, 85% of tribal youth admitted to the jurisdiction of the Federal Bureau of Prisons (BOP) were from these five federal judicial districts: Arizona, Montana, New Mexico, North Dakota, and South Dakota (figure 5.3). The most recent tribal population data from the Bureau of Indian Affairs (2005) showed that these five districts contained 12% of the 590 federally recognized tribal entities and 35% of the more than 1.9 million total tribal enrollment population (table 5.2). Thirty-four percent of the enrolled tribal population under age 16 resided on or near reservations in these five federal judicial districts. Table 5.2 Federally recognized tribes and enrolled members, 2005 Tribal entities Tribal enrollment Tribal population under age 16 Federal judicial district Number Percent Number Percent District rank Number Percent of total enrollment District rank Total 590 100% 1,978,099 100% ~ 503,958 100% ~ Arizona 22 3.7% 269,778 13.6% 2 70,854 14.1% 2 New Mexico 25 4.2 174,199 8.8 3 43,234 8.6 4 South Dakota 8 1.4 115,513 5.8 5 27,534 5.5 6 Montana 8 1.4 66,962 3.4 6 14,957 3 9 North Dakota 6 1 58,220 2.9 8 13,851 2.7 10 All other districts 521 88.3 1,293,427 65.4 ~ 333,528 66.2 ~ ~Not available. Source: U.S. Department of the Interior, Bureau of Indian Affairs. American Indian Population and Labor Force Report, 2005, available at: http://www.bia.gov/ WhatWeDo/Knowledge/Reports/index.htm, calendar year 2005. 45–87 16–4416–44 1–151–15 0 District of Arizona (14%) District of New Mexico (12%) District of Montana (28%) District of North Dakota (4%) District of South Dakota (27%) Number of tribal youth admitted Figure 5.3 Tribal youth admitted to the jurisdiction of the Federal Bureau of Prisons, and five federal judicial districts that committed the majority of tribal youth, 2006–2008 Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics analysis of data from the Federal Bureau of Prisons, SENTRY database, fiscal years 2006–2008. Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 39 Adjudication and Sentencing Federal statutes provide for a youth’s release pending trial to a parent/ guardian, unless it is determined that detention is necessary to ensure a timely appearance or to ensure safety of juveniles or others (Title 18 U.S.C. § 5034). The federal pretrial services agency oversees supervision of the youth on pretrial release. For juveniles detained, a foster home or community-based facility near the youth’s home community is sought. Pretrial juveniles are not to be detained in facilities permitting regular contact with adult offenders nor with other juveniles who have been adjudicated. In 2008, 91% of cases terminated in U.S. district court involving tribal youth resulted in conviction Most (91%) tribal youth cases terminated ended in conviction in 2008. Most of the convictions were the result of a guilty plea (88%) than a determination of guilt at trial (3%). In comparison, 95% of non-tribal youth were convicted in 2008, with 91% resulting from guilty pleas and 5% following trial. From 2004 to 2008, the average conviction rate for tribal youth (92%) was higher than for non- tribal youth (87%). In juvenile adjudication proceedings, the judge has the discretion to impose an out-of-home placement, probation and conditions of probation, or restitution. The youth may also be transferred to adult status and prosecuted and sentenced as an adult. An adjudicated juvenile can receive up to 3 years of probation. The duration of a sentence for youth adjudicated delinquent to the jurisdiction of federal prison authorities depends on the age of the juvenile at disposition (see text box below). Juveniles under the age of 18 are not allowed to be placed in an institution in which the youth has regular contact with incarcerated adults. A juvenile can be housed in a Federal Bureau of Prisons (BOP) institution at the age of 21 if sentenced as a juvenile. The maximum time under federal jurisdiction of juveniles adjudicated delinquent depends on the age at disposition � If a juvenile was under 18 years of age at time of disposition, detention may not extend beyond the juvenile reaching age 21 (figure 5.4). � If a juvenile was between the ages of 18 and 21 at time of disposition, the maximum federal jurisdiction is 5 years. � Juveniles adjudicated delinquent and under the age of 21 are not to be detained in facilities permitting regular contact with adult convicts. At age 21, however, an adjudicated delinquent can be placed in an adult facility. � The term that an adjudicated delinquent receives may not exceed the maximum period of imprisonment authorized had the juvenile been an adult. Federal sentencing guidelines do not apply to adjudications of delinquency. 11 or younger 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 Maximum age in federal jurisdiction is 21 if age at disposition is under 18 years Age at disposition Maximum age of federal jurisdiction For disposition between ages 18 and 21, the maximum length of federal jurisdiction is 5 years Age of delinquent at disposition Figure 5.4 Maximum time under federal jurisdiction of juveniles adjudicated delinquent, by age at disposition Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201140 Corrections The number of tribal youth admitted to BOP jurisdiction increased from 107 in 1994 to a peak of 252 in 2000— a 136% increase due exclusively to the growth in tribal youth handled as adjudicated delinquents (figure 5.5). The number of tribal youth admitted to the BOP subsequently decreased from 252 in 2000 to 72 in 2008. In 2008, the number of tribal (72) and non-tribal youth (84) admitted to the jurisdiction of federal prison authorities was the lowest in the period from 1994 to 2008. From 1999 to 2008, the number of tribal youth admissions declined an annual average of 10%, and non-tribal admissions declined at an annual average of 12%. Tribal youth peaked at 252 admissions in 2000, and non- tribal youth peaked at 272 admissions in 1999 (figure 5.6). Most (88%) of the decline in tribal youth from 1999 to 2008 was due to a decrease in youth who had been adjudicated delinquent. Twelve percent of the decline was due to a decrease in tribal youth who had been transferred to adult status. In comparison, most of the decline for non-tribal youth admitted to the BOP over this period was comprised of juveniles who had been transferred to adult status. In 2008, 72% of tribal youth were admitted to BOP jurisdiction for a violent offense, including sexual abuse (29%), assault (25%), and murder (15%) (table 5.3). Tribal youth admitted for property offenses (mostly burglary) peaked in 2000 (66) and began to decline in 2001, dropping to 14 admissions in 2008. By 2008, tribal youth admitted to BOP jurisdiction for both property and violent offenses had declined to the lowest levels since 1999. Among non-tribal youth admitted to BOP jurisdiction, violent and drug offenses comprised the majority of offense types (not shown in table). Most tribal youth admitted to BOP jurisdiction from 1999 to 2008 had been adjudicated delinquent (83%), while most non-tribal youth had been prosecuted as adults (65%). 0 50 100 150 200 250 300 Tribal-transferred as adult Tribal-adjudicated delinquent 200820072006200520042003200220012000199919981997199619951994 Number of tribal youth Fiscal year Figure 5.5 Tribal youth admitted to the jurisdiction of the Federal Bureau of Prisons, by status at admission, 1994–2008 Note: Data for fiscal years 1999–2008 based on Urban Institute analysis of Federal Bureau of Prisons, SENTRY database. Data for fiscal years 1994–1998 based on BJS analysis of SENTRY data. 0 50 100 150 200 250 300 Non-tribal-transferred as adult Non-tribal-adjudicated delinquent 200820072006200520042003200220012000199919981997199619951994 Number of non-tribal youth Fiscal year Figure 5.6 Non-tribal youth admitted to the jurisdiction of the Federal Bureau of Prisons, by status at admission, 1994–2008 Note: Data for fiscal years 1999–2008 based on Urban Institute analysis of Federal Bureau of Prisons, SENTRY database. Data for fiscal years 1994–1998 based on BJS analysis of SENTRY data. Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 41 At yearend 2003, 298 tribal youth were in BOP facilities, including both juvenile contract and adult facilities In 2003, 74% of tribal youth were housed under BOP jurisdiction in Minnesota, Arizona, Utah, the Western District of Texas, and Colorado. BOP facilities (including contract facilities) were not located in the states that contained large tribal populations and had committed a large number of Indian country juveniles (South Dakota, North Dakota, Montana, and New Mexico). For example, tribal youth whose legal residence was South Dakota comprised over half of the juveniles in BOP facilities in Minnesota. Among tribal youth under BOP jurisdiction in 2003, most were committed for a violent felony offense, including homicide, manslaughter, serious sexual assault or abuse, and serious physical assault. In comparison, 185 tribal juveniles were in custody in 10 juvenile tribal facilities in 2002. (See American Indians and Crime, BJS Web, December 2004.) These tribal youth were confined mostly for misdemeanor (62%) and status offenses (29%); 10% of the youth were confined in tribal juvenile facilities for felony offenses. Table 5.3 Tribal youth admitted to the jurisdiction of the Federal Bureau of Prisons, 1999–2008 Year of commitment to BOP jurisdiction Commitment offense Total 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 2008 Total 1,909 241 252 219 234 212 231 208 164 76 72 Murder/Negligent manslaughter* 218 31 27 25 18 20 24 26 20 16 11 Assault 491 44 65 70 57 52 64 52 49 20 18 Robbery 51 7 5 9 4 7 9 4 3 1 2 Sexual abuse 441 55 52 33 65 46 55 57 40 17 21 Embezzlement 1 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 Burglary 442 62 66 59 61 53 43 42 30 12 14 Larceny 56 12 7 5 8 4 4 6 6 2 2 Motor vehicle theft 8 2 1 1 0 1 0 1 2 0 0 Arson and explosives 69 2 6 3 5 11 17 9 6 7 3 Other property offenses 38 13 6 6 4 1 3 3 1 1 0 Other drug felonies 3 0 1 0 0 1 0 1 0 0 0 Weapon offenses 9 1 2 0 2 1 2 1 0 0 0 Nonviolent sex offenses 36 4 4 1 4 7 7 3 5 0 1 Traffic offenses 13 2 5 1 1 3 1 0 0 0 0 Note: Total includes juveniles whose offenses were missing or unclassifiable. *Includes attempted murder. Source: Urban Institute analysis of Federal Bureau of Prisons, SENTRY data base, fiscal years 1999-2008. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201142 Tribal youth served a sentence in federal facilities that was twice as long as the maximum sentence tribal facilities can impose From 1999 to 2008, the average time served by tribal youth tended to be longer (about 26 months, on average) than the tribal justice system maximum sentence of 12 months. The Tribal Law and Order Act of 2010 recently extended the maximum a tribal court can sentence to 3 years for those courts meeting conditions placed on the legal process. The average time served by non-tribal youth in BOP facilities more than doubled from 15 months in 1999 to over 38 months by 2008. Non-tribal youth admitted to the federal prison authorities were somewhat more dispersed than tribal youth with respect to district of commitment About 32% of non-tribal youth were committed from the five federal districts that committed the most tribal youth. Thirty-six percent of non-tribal youth were committed to the BOP from five federal judicial districts along the U.S.-Mexico border: California-Southern, Arizona, New Mexico, Texas-Western, and Texas-Southern. (figure 5.7). Among juveniles admitted to the jurisdiction of the BOP in 2008, non- tribal youth were slightly older at age of offense than tribal youth The average of age tribal youth at time of offense was about 15 years compared to 16 years for non-tribal youth. Most tribal youth were male (92%), American Indian (96%), non- Hispanic (99%), and United States citizens (100%). The majority of non- tribal youth were male (93%), white (60%), non-Hispanic (58%), and United States citizens (71%). 26–6026–60 10–2510–25 1–91–9 00 Number of non-tribal youth admittedNumber of non-tribal youth admitted District of Arizona (19%) New Mexico (5%) District of Western Texas (7%) District of Eastern New York (4%)District of South Dakota (3%) Figure 5.7 Non-tribal youth admitted to the jurisdiction of the Federal Bureau of Prisons, and five federal judicial districts that committed the majority of non-tribal youth, 2006–2008 Source: Based on BJS analysis of data from the Federal Bureau of Prisons, SENTRY database, fiscal years 2006–2008. Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 43 Methodology The primary source of data presented in this report is from the Federal Justice Statistics Program (FJSP). The methodology to identify tribal youth was developed by the Urban Institute, and primary findings reported here are drawn from their 2011 study, Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System (http://ncjrs.gov). This report supplemented findings from the Urban Institute’s study with additional analyses based on BJS analysis of FJSP data. Data from the Federal Bureau of Prisons (BOP), SENTRY database, which contains information on all federally sentenced offenders admitted to BOP jurisdiction at fiscal yearend were analyzed for the years 1994 to 1998. The source of the data in figure 5.1 is The Urban Institute analysis of Executive Office for U.S. Attorneys, National LIONS database, fiscal years 2000 to 2008. Suspects in matters concluded include all matters which were concluded in each respective year. Suspects in matters prosecuted include matters for which the U.S. attorneys in that district made the decision to prosecute the matter in each fiscal year. The unit of count for figure 5.1 is the suspect matter. A matter is a referral on which an attorney spends one hour or more investigating, and on which formal papers have not been filed with the Court. If a decision is made not to continue with the investigation, it is disposed of in the LIONS database by declination and closed. References American Indians and Crime, NCJ 203097, BJS Web, December 2004. 2005 American Indian Population and Labor Force Report. U.S. Department of the Interior, Bureau of Indian Affairs, 2005. The Urban Institute. Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System, NCJ 234549, May 2011. Available at http://ncjrs.gov. Researchers from The Urban Institute investigated how youth from Indian Country were processed by the federal criminal justice system. They used a combination of qualitative and quantitative information, including administrative data from the BJS-sponsored Federal Justice Statistics Program (FJSP) and information drawn from interviews with more than three dozen federal and tribal justice system personnel. Staff at the Urban Institute who contributed to the study included— Co-principal Investigators William Adams and Julie Samuels Contextual Analysis Team Janeen Buck Willison Hannah Dodd Meredith Dank Quantitative Analysis Team Barbara Parthasarathy Kamala Mallik Kane Jessica Kelly Sybil Mendonca KiDeuk Kim Office of Justice Programs Innovation • Partnerships • Safer Neighborhoods http://www.ojp.gov work_f5gerpyfjbhm7lize3dd64gyqm ---- econstor Make Your Publications Visible. A Service of zbw Leibniz-Informationszentrum Wirtschaft Leibniz Information Centre for Economics Ash, Michael; Boyce, James K. Working Paper Measuring corporate environmental justice performance Working Paper, No. 2008-16 Provided in Cooperation with: Department of Economics, University of Massachusetts Suggested Citation: Ash, Michael; Boyce, James K. (2008) : Measuring corporate environmental justice performance, Working Paper, No. 2008-16, University of Massachusetts, Department of Economics, Amherst, MA This Version is available at: http://hdl.handle.net/10419/64231 Standard-Nutzungsbedingungen: Die Dokumente auf EconStor dürfen zu eigenen wissenschaftlichen Zwecken und zum Privatgebrauch gespeichert und kopiert werden. Sie dürfen die Dokumente nicht für öffentliche oder kommerzielle Zwecke vervielfältigen, öffentlich ausstellen, öffentlich zugänglich machen, vertreiben oder anderweitig nutzen. Sofern die Verfasser die Dokumente unter Open-Content-Lizenzen (insbesondere CC-Lizenzen) zur Verfügung gestellt haben sollten, gelten abweichend von diesen Nutzungsbedingungen die in der dort genannten Lizenz gewährten Nutzungsrechte. Terms of use: Documents in EconStor may be saved and copied for your personal and scholarly purposes. You are not to copy documents for public or commercial purposes, to exhibit the documents publicly, to make them publicly available on the internet, or to distribute or otherwise use the documents in public. If the documents have been made available under an Open Content Licence (especially Creative Commons Licences), you may exercise further usage rights as specified in the indicated licence. www.econstor.eu DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS Working Paper UNIVERSITY OF MASSACHUSETTS AMHERST Measuring Corporate Environmental Justice Performance by Michael Ash and James K. Boyce Working Paper 2008-16 Measuring Corporate Environmental Justice Performance∗ Michael Ash† James K. Boyce‡ October 31, 2008 Abstract Measures of corporate environmental justice performance can be a valuable tool in efforts to promote corporate social responsibility and to document systematic patterns of environmental injustice. This paper develops such a measure based on the extent to which toxic air emissions from industrial facilities disproportionately impact racial and ethnic minorities and low-income people. Applying the measure to 100 major corporate air polluters in the United States, we find wide variation in the extent of disproportional exposures. In a number of cases, minorities bear more than half of the total human health impacts from the firm’s industrial air pollution. Keywords: Corporate social responsibility; corporate environmental performance; environmental justice; air pollution JEL codes: M14, Q52, Q56 1 Introduction This paper analyzes corporate environmental justice performance, measured in terms of the human health impacts of airborne emissions of toxic chemicals from their industrial facili- ties. Prior studies of corporate environmental performance (CEP) have focused primarily on total emissions of pollutants, remediation efforts, or aggregate environmental damage. Prior studies of environmental justice (EJ) have examined the extent to which hazards dispropor- tionately impact specific groups, such as racial minorities. To the best of our knowledge, this paper is the first effort to combine these two strands of research by building a measure of corporate environmental justice performance (CEJP). ∗Corresponding author: Michael Ash, Department of Economics, Thompson Hall, University of Mas- sachusetts, Amherst, MA 01003; mash@econs.umass.edu. Acknowledgments: We thank the Ford Foun- dation and the V.K. Rasmussen Foundation for support of the research. Bengi Akbulut, Grace Chang, Rich Puchalsky, Helen Scharber, Gül Ünal, and Ann Werboff provided outstanding research assistance and data management. The authors alone bear responsibility for the analysis. †Associate Professor, Department of Economics, Center for Public Policy and Administration, and Polit- ical Economy Research Institute, University of Massachusetts, Amherst ‡Professor, Department of Economics and Political Economy Research Institute, University of Mas- sachusetts, Amherst 1 The difference between CEP and EJ studies is partly methodological: in CEP, the unit of analysis is the source of pollution, the firm or an individual facility; in EJ, the unit of analysis is the receptor, the community or households on the receiving end. They also differ in their audiences and aims. The main audience for CEP research is socially responsible managers, investors, and consumers, with the main aim being to improve firm behavior. The main audience for EJ research is the impacted communities and the responsible government officials, the main aim being to protect communities from disproportionate hazards. This paper presents a measure of corporate environmental justice performance, in an effort to bridge the gap between CEP and EJ research. Our measure is based on data that link pollution exposures to pollution sources. The audiences for this work span the CEP and EJ audiences, including both corporate social responsibility advocates who want information about this important dimension of environmental performance, and environmental justice advocates who want documentation on systematic patterns in corporate behavior. The paper is organized as follows. In Section 2, we describe the datasets and methodology for matching the exposure and Census data. Our environmental data come from a source-and-receptor model of air-toxics release and exposure from the U.S. Environment Protection Agency (EPA). We merge the EPA data with socioeconomic data from the U.S. Bureau of the Census to analyze expo- sure disparities by race, ethnicity, and income. This facility-level information is aggregated to obtain firm-level measures using a dataset on corporate ownership of industrial facilities developed at the Political Economy Research Institute (PERI) of the University of Mas- sachusetts, Amherst. In Section 3, we present the CEJP measure, and report the results of applying it to 100 corporations operating throughout the United States. The corporations are those listed in the latest edition of PERI’s “Toxic 100,” which uses the same data sources to rank the largest firms in the country on the basis of total human health hazards resulting from air toxics emissions at their facilities. In Section 4, we present “worst-in-class” and “best-in-class” rankings for firms in two industrial sectors that rank high in their air toxics emissions: oil refining; and plastics and synthetic materials. Community-based EJ activists generally have focused on impacts from specific facilities, such as the Solutia (former Monsanto) plant in Anniston, Alabama.1 Whether the exposure patterns at individual facilities can be generalized to overall corporate behavior is seldom evident. Academic EJ researchers generally have focused on the aggregate pollution loads imposed on people of color and low-income communities, rather than iden- tifying specific sources of these burdens.2 Whatever the overall extent of disproportionate impacts, there is no reason to assume that disparities are constant across firms. We show that the extent to which firms even in the same industrial sector impose disparate pollution burdens on different groups can and does vary substantially. In Section 5, we examine the relationship between CEJP and the measure of total hu- man health risk for the Toxic 100, with the dual aims of assessing whether a measure of 1On the Anniston case, see U.S. Senate Committee on Appropriations [2002] and Bryan [2003]. 2See, for example, Ash and Fetter [2004], Pastor et al. [2006], and Mohai and Saha [2007]. 2 environmental justice performance adds value to a more conventional measure of CEP, and of testing the hypothesis that performance in these two dimensions, while not identical, is positively correlated. In Section 6, we conclude by discussing potential uses of these data in research on the determinants and effects of CEJP and in efforts to improve corporate performance. 2 Data and Methods The underlying data for the CEJP measure come from three sources: the EPA’s Risk- Screening Environmental Indicators (RSEI); the 2000 U.S. Census of Population and Hous- ing; and the PERI corporation-facility identification dataset. This section describes these data sources and how we merge them in order to construct our measure of corporate envi- ronmental justice performance. 2.1 The RSEI project First, we describe two sets of data emerging from the EPA’s RSEI project: the aggregated version which is contained in the EPA’s RSEI public-release data; and the disaggregated RSEI Geographic Microdata (RSEI-GM) which currently are not available to the public at large. Our measure relies on the latter, but it is useful first to describe the public-release data. 2.1.1 The RSEI Project and Public-Release Data Estimates of exposure to airborne toxics emitted by industrial facilities across the United States are generated by the RSEI project of EPA. The RSEI project starts with information on annual releases of more than 600 chemicals from more than 20,000 facilities, reported in the Toxics Release Inventory (TRI). It then incorporates data on the relative toxicity of these chemicals, their fate and transport (taking into account chemical breakdown rates, stack heights, exit-gas velocities, prevailing wind currents, etc.) and the resulting exposures. For each air release (that is, each facility-chemical pair), RSEI estimates exposures in each square kilometer of a 101 km × 101 km grid centered on the facility. The EPA publicly releases facility-level measures of the resulting human health hazards, aggregated over the 10,201 one km-sq cells within the grid and across chemicals. These “RSEI scores” are used by federal and state environmental officials to prioritize enforcement actions. The TRI was created at the direction of the Congress under the Emergency Planning and Community Right-to-Know Act passed in 1986 after the Bhopal chemical plant disaster. The Act requires industrial facilities to submit annual data to EPA on deliberate and accidental releases of roughly 600 toxic chemicals into air, surface water, and the ground. TRI data are available on an annual basis starting in 1987. In 2005, more than 20,000 TRI-reporting facilities released a total of 1.5 billion pounds of toxic chemicals into the air, and additional toxics were released from offsite incinerators. The TRI is widely used in both CEP and EJ literature: CEP studies typically use TRI data on the total mass (pounds) of emissions, while EJ studies typically analyze the geographical distribution of TRI-reporting facilities in relation to the demographics of the communities in which they are located. The TRI data are the jewel in the crown of the environmental “right-to-know” movement 3 in the United States. But valuable as they are, the TRI data have important limitations. Some of these stem from the nature of the data: the releases are annual totals, estimated, self-reported, and limited to listed chemicals from qualifying facilities and processes. One of the most significant limitations is that the TRI simply reports pounds of chemical releases, often generating press stories that identify local “top polluters” on this basis. Such reporting does not account for variations in the toxicity of different chemicals, some of which, pound- for pound, are as much as ten million times more toxic than others. Nor does it take into account the fate and transport of these chemicals in the environment, or the number of people impacted. Finally, because the TRI reports facility-by-facility data, the cumulative impact on communities that are affected by multiple facilities is not evident.3 The RSEI project was launched by the EPA in the mid-1990s to address several of these limitations. The EPA Office of Pollution Prevention and Toxics (OPPT) processes the TRI data on the quantity of each chemical released by each facility to create the RSEI. To assess the human health risks posed by each release, the EPA combines this with information on: (1) toxicity, or how dangerous the chemical is in terms of chronic human health effects; (2) fate and transport, or how the chemical spreads from the point of release to the surrounding area; and (3) population exposure, or how many people live in the affected areas and are exposed to inhalation of different concentrations of the chemical. Each air release begins at a stack, leaking valve, open canister, or other source within the facility, or at the stack of an offsite incineration facility to which it ships wastes. The In- dustrial Source Complex-Long Term (ISCLT3) model, a Gaussian-plume fate-and-transport model, is used to map how the chemical spreads from the point of release in the surround- ing geography.4 EPA combines data on temperature and local wind patterns with facility- specific information on smokestack height and the exit velocity of released gases, together with chemical-specific information on molecular weight and rates of deposition and decay, to estimate the ambient concentrations of each release in each square kilometer within a 101 km by 101 km grid (10,201 sq km) around each facility. By multiplying the mass (pounds) of each chemical by a toxicity weight, EPA compares the toxicological significance of releases of different chemicals. The EPA’s toxicity-weighting system is based on peer-reviewed databases from several sources: the EPA’s Integrated Risk Information System (IRIS); the EPA’s Office of Pesticide Programs (OPP) Reference Dose Tracking Reports; the U.S. Department of Health and Human Services Agency for Toxic Substances and Disease Registry (ATSDR); the California Environmental Protection Agency (CalEPA) Office of Environmental Health Hazard and Assessment (OEHHA); and the EPA’s Health Effects Assessment Tables (HEAST). For some chemicals listed in the 3The TRI data capture the largest point-source air pollution emissions in the United States, but they do not capture emissions from mobile sources, such as trucks, automobiles, ships, and aircraft. The TRI also excludes facilities that are not required to report by virtue of small size or belonging to non-listed industrial sectors. Potentially significant air polluters not covered for these reasons include gas stations, dry cleaners, and auto-body shops. 4Geographic buffers based on plume modeling provide a more accurate picture of exposure to industrial air releases than do simple circular or distance-weighted buffers [Chakraborty and Armstrong, 1997, Saha and Mohai, 2005]. 4 TRI, no consensus has been reached on the appropriate toxicity weight, and these chemicals are currently excluded from the RSEI public-release data. In recent years, the excluded chemicals have represented about one percent of the total mass of reported toxic air releases nationwide. Although all TRI chemicals are hazardous, their toxicities vary widely. For carcinogens, the EPA’s toxicity-weighting system uses inhalation-based dose-response estimates of the excess lifetime cancer risk per unit of concentration. The toxicity-weighted concentration is proportional to an individual’s excess risk of cancer from that concentration. For non- carcinogens, the toxicity-weighting system uses the “Reference Concentration,” which is the highest level of exposure concentration with no adverse health impact, and expresses toxicity-weighted exposures as multiples of this (for example, “six times the highest safe concentration”). Equivalence between the non-carcinogenic and carcinogenic scales has been set by the EPA Science Advisory Board at a Reference Concentration being equivalent to a carcinogenic risk of 250 excess cancer cases per million persons. At the extreme ends of the resulting toxicity scale for the chemicals on the TRI list, one pound of friable asbestos is equivalent, in terms of inhalation toxicity, to 27 million pounds of chlorodifluoromethane (HCFC-22). The RSEI project overlays the grid of toxicity-weighted air pollution concentrations upon a grid of population data drawn from block-level data from the U.S. Census. The calculation of aggregate human health risk is based on population exposure to given toxicity-weighted concentrations. In addition to the number of people in each one-square-kilometer grid cell, the RSEI’s population weights take into account the age and sex composition of the popu- lation, because exposure varies by the volume of air inhaled per unit of body weight.5 The RSEI score for a given release (facility-chemical) affecting a given grid cell is: RSEI Scoref cg = ∑ a ∑ s Populatonasg × IEFas × Toxicityc × Concentrationf cg (2.1) where Populatonasg is the population of sex s in age category a in cell g; IEFas is the inhalation factor for persons of sex s in age category a; Toxicityc is the toxicity weight for chemical c; and Concentrationf cg is the estimated concentration from the plume model at cell g for chemical c released by facility f. The release-cell score, measuring the impact of a given release on a given cell, represents the total human health risk for the population exposed in that location. In the case of carcinogens, this score is directly proportional to the number of excess statistical cancer cases. The EPA’s main objective in creating the RSEI was to assist federal and state agencies in setting priorities for environmental protection. To this end, the release-cell scores are 5The population-exposure values reflect the cubic meters of air inhaled by a person (roughly 20 cubic meters per 70 kg) per day. Inhalation exposure factors ranging from 0.165 to 0.341 are used to convert toxicity-weighted air concentrations into human exposures, according to the following formula: 0.341×(count of males, aged 0 to 17) + 0.209×(males, 18 to 44) + 0.194×(males, 45 to 64) + 0.174×(males, 65 and Up) + 0.310×(females, aged 0 to 17) + 0.186×(females, 18 to 44) + 0.165×(females, 45 to 64) + 0.153×(females, 65 and Up). 5 aggregated (across chemicals and cells) on a facility-by-facility basis: RSEI Scoref = ∑ c ∑ g RSEI Scoref cg (2.2) The facility-wise RSEI scores are made available to government agencies and the public on the RSEI public-release data CD-ROM, available for free from EPA. The public-release data include information on the contribution of each chemical to the facility’s RSEI score, but they do not include disaggregated information on the geographic cells impacted by the toxic releases. The RSEI methodology described above has been subjected to extensive internal and external reviews, including a peer review by external risk-assessment experts, three peer reviews by the EPA’s Science Advisory Board, peer reviews by the States, and submission for public comment.6 2.1.2 The RSEI Geographic Microdata (RSEI-GM) Because EPA developed the RSEI data for the purpose of prioritizing facilities (that is, sources) for enforcement and clean-up, the public-release data are not designed for examining differences among communities (that is, receptors) in terms of their exposure to industrial toxic releases. The CEJP measure requires use of the disaggregated RSEI-GM data, which provide 1 km2 cell-by-cell estimates of exposure to airborne toxics identified by source facility and chemical. The disaggregated data are not available to the public, owing to their daunting size and complexity. EPA has, however, made the geographic microdata available to the research community. At an earlier stage, EPA provided partially disaggregated RSEI data on total estimated health hazards from air toxics for each of the roughly two million impacted 1 km2 grid cells. These data were not fully disaggregated; instead they were summed over all releases, i.e., aggregated on a cell-by-cell basis across facilities (sources) and chemicals. The aggregate RSEI score for a cell g is RSEI Scoreg = ∑ f ∑ c RSEI Scoref cg (2.3) where f indexes facility and c indexes chemical. Although these earlier data provided no distinction among sources, the total human health risk was measured at fine geographic resolution. By merging this receptor-based measure of aggregate hazards with Census data, two published EJ studies [Bouwes et al., 2003, Ash and Fetter, 2004] have analyzed hazards in relation to race, ethnicity, and income using these data for the years 1997 and 1998, re- spectively. These studies found statistically significant evidence of disproportionate impacts, both by race and ethnicity (controlling for income) and by income (controlling for race and ethnicity). To develop corporation-specific measures of EJ performance, we must use the fully dis- aggregated geographic microdata, which identify impacts by source facility and receptor cell 6For details, see Office of Pollution Prevention and Toxics [2004]. 6 (RSEI scoref g). The RSEI-GM data provide this information. Unlike most other data used in the investigation of environmental inequalities, the RSEI-GM data offer: 1. National scope and coverage of a wide range of industries, chemicals, and facilities. The RSEI-GM data include almost all (99 percent by weight) of the air releases reported to the TRI. The TRI is the most comprehensive list of industrial toxic releases in the United States, in 2005 covering 494 chemicals and chemical groups released by 23,438 facilities in manufacturing, metal mining, electrical power generation, waste storage and processing, and chemical storage, as well as Federal facilities. The criteria for inclusion in TRI reporting include industrial sector and the quantity of toxic chemicals processed at the facility. 2. Fate, transport, and exposure modeling of all national releases at precise geographic resolution. The fate-and-transport model permits the unbiased measurement of expo- sure at receptor sites resulting from point-source air releases, with a high degree of geographic specificity.7 The focus on exposure at the receptor site outflanks the “How near is near?” debate in the environmental justice literature as to what distance best fits the notion of “closeness” to a point source (for discussion, see Boyce [2007]). 3. Identification of the source facility for each pollutant release. The data on ambient con- centrations of toxics at receptor sites are disaggregated by source facility and chemical. Unlike the Global Emissions Monitoring System (GEMS) and other pollution-exposure data based on aggregate levels of pollutants at the receptor site, the RSEI-GM makes it possible to track each exposure to its source. The simultaneous identification of source and exposure is perhaps the most important and distinctive strength of the RSEI-GM. 4. Nearly twenty years of annual data spanning the decennial Censuses of 1990 and 2000. The RSEI-GM time series makes it possible to conduct innovative temporal analysis. Much of the debate over causality and policy in the environmental justice literature has revolved around matters of timing: which came first, the people or the pollution? Longitudinal studies can help us understand the dynamic processes of demographic and environmental change. 5. Toxicity weighting, expressing the human health risk of emissions per quantity re- leased. The EPA’s toxicity-weighting system permits comparison of toxic releases from disparate industrial processes. 6. Construction by well-documented methods that have undergone extensive peer review. The EPA’s RSEI data are among the most rigorously reviewed environmental datasets in the nation, and they carry the imprimatur of the Federal regulatory authorities. In summary, the RSEI-GM database offers a remarkable tool for the analysis of envi- ronmental justice issues in the United States. Its fine geographic resolution exceeds that 7The 1 square-km resolution of the data does not exhaust the power of the plume model; rather, the trade-off between geographic specificity and database size determines the scale. 7 of other national exposure databases, such as the National Air Toxics Assessment (NATA). By measuring exposure, it circumvents the how-near-is-near problem that has plagued EJ studies based simply on proximity to point sources. Disaggregation by source and chemical permits the identification of problematic and improving industrial sectors and processes. The linkage of release and exposure—that is, source and receptor—provided by the RSEI-GM is unparalleled by any other national dataset. The longitudinal character of the data enables time-series and panel analyses that can shed light on trends as well as levels of exposure, and on the dynamic interplay between demographic and environmental change. The RSEI-GM data thus extend the range and complexity of EJ research questions that can be feasibly addressed. In this paper, we show how the data can be used to measure corporate environmental justice performance. 2.2 Census of Population & Housing: The Spatial Join The 2000 U.S. Census of Population and Housing provides the social, economic, and demo- graphic data for construction of our measure. Census blocks, defined by roads and other geographic features, are the smallest geographic unit of data published by the Census. The data provided at this level include counts of the race, sex, and age of residents. With the help of local committees, the Census Bureau defines Census block groups, which typically contain roughly 30 blocks that correspond to neighborhoods, a method that ensures a degree of socioeconomic homogeneity. Block groups contain 600 to 3,000 people.8 The block group is the smallest geographic unit for which the Census Bureau publicly releases socioeconomic data, including counts of the number of people in poverty. The Census and RSEI-GM data are well-matched in terms of geographic precision, but they are not in the same geographic format. The RSEI-GM model divides the United States, including Puerto Rico, into one-square-kilometer cells, of which seven million are within the 101 km × 101 km catchment of at least one industrial facility and almost three million have positive toxics exposure. Census blocks and block groups have irregular boundaries, and they can be larger or smaller than one square kilometer. Working with the EPA, its contractor, and a consortium of academic researchers, we constructed a crosswalk by which Census geography is spatially joined with the 1 km2 grid-cell data.9 For every cell, the crosswalk calculates the fraction of the total area of each block that falls into it. In this way we can count, by age category and sex, the number of poor people, blacks, Latinos, Asian-Americans, Native Americans, and non-Hispanic whites in each of the 1 km2 cells: Populationrasg = ∑ b αgb × Populationrasb (2.4) where Populationrasg is the estimated population of race or ethnicity r, age a, and sex s in cell g; Populationrasb is the population of race r, age a, and sex s in Census block b, and αgb is the share of Census block b that lies in grid cell g. The year 2000 Populationrasb of Census 8Block groups fully partition Census tracts, the next level of aggregation, which on average contain 4,000 residents. 9In addition to the authors, other members of the RSEI-GM research consortium are based at the Uni- versity of Michigan, the University of Southern California, and the University of California, Berkeley. 8 block b is extracted from the Summary File 1 data from the Census. The crosswalk term, αgb, is used by the EPA to incorporate population densities in the RSEI project. Using this method, we obtained age-sex-race/ethnicity population counts for each grid cell g. Our race/ethnicity population counts, segmented by age-group and sex, were derived at the 1 km2 grid-cell level from the block-grid spatial merge, using exactly the same method that the EPA’s RSEI model uses in its total population counts. We then compute: RSEI Scorerf cg = ∑ a ∑ s Populatonrasg × IEFas × Toxicityc × Concentrationf cg (2.5) where Populationrasg is the race or ethnicity r, age a, and sex s population of cell g. Summing over the 10,201 cells around each facility, the score expresses the aggregate health risk to minority group r from exposure to a given release: RSEI Scorerf c = ∑ g RSEI Scorerf cg (2.6) For the impact from all of the releases from a single facility, RSEI Scorerf = ∑ c ∑ g RSEI Scorerf cg (2.7) The Census does not report income data at the block level, but only at the block-group level and higher aggregations (in Census Summary File 3). For this reason, the poverty- specific population counts are derived from a spatial merge of block-group data with the grid cells.10 We tested whether applying this broader block-group aggregation to the racial/ethnic population data caused results to vary much from those obtained from the spatial merge at the finer block level, and found that there is little difference in the results. 2.3 Corporation-facility matching To develop corporate performance measures, one more step is required: matching individual facilities to their corporate parents. PERI’s Corporate Toxics Information Project (CTIP) has developed a dataset for this purpose. This parent-facility matching requires continu- ous updating to track mergers and acquisitions, transfers of facilities to new owners, and the entry of new facilities into the TRI and RSEI databases. Extracting information on company ownership of facilities from the TRI reports, Dun & Bradstreet’s Million Dollar Database, Mergent Online, http://www.hoovers.com, company websites, printed reports, and telephone calls, the CTIP matches facilities to their parent companies. By aggregating the RSEI scores of the facilities owned by individual parent companies, the CTIP produces “The Toxic 100,” a ranking of the largest corporations operating in the 10The Census poverty data are reported by age-group but not by sex, and the age-groups are less disag- gregated than those at the block level used by the RSEI model: where RSEI distinguishes 18 to 44 and 45 to 64, the Census block-group data on the poor report 18 to 64 as a single category. Hence we averaged the age-specific exposure factors for males and females; for example, (0.341 + 0.310) / 2 = 0.326 for persons aged 0 to 17. For the combined age group, we computed a span-weighted average: (27/47×(0.209 + 0.186)/2 + 20/47×(0.194+0.165))/2) = 0.190 for persons aged 18 to 64. 9 http://www.hoovers.com United States on the basis of the total human health risk from air toxics emissions from their facilities, as measured by the RSEI data. The most recent edition of the Toxic 100 (available at http://www.peri.umass.edu/toxic100/) identifies the top polluters among the companies that appeared in the year 2007 on the Fortune 500, Fortune Global 500, and S&P 500 lists of the country’s largest corporations, and on the Forbes Global 2000 list of the largest 500 U.S.-based and 500 foreign-based corporations. The most recent available RSEI data from EPA refer to the year 2005. The Toxic 100 therefore reports 2005 air pollution from industrial facilities in the United States, based on the latest available (2007) data on ownership structure. 3 A Measure of Corporate Environmental Justice Performance In this section we present our measure of corporate environmental justice performance (CEJP) for the 100 large firms that appear in the latest edition of PERI’s Toxic 100. The measure indicates the extent to which the human health impacts from releases of toxic air pollutants at industrial facilities owned by the corporation are borne by specific subgroups of the U.S. population. Two CEJP indicators are reported here: the first measures impacts on racial and ethnic minorities, and the second measures impacts on people with incomes below the national poverty line. 3.1 Measuring group shares of human health risk To measure human health risk for a given corporation, we aggregate the race/ethnicity- specific and poverty-specific scores for the facilities it owns: RSEI ScorerF = ∑ f∈F RSEI Scorerf (3.1) where r indexes racial/ethnic or poverty categories, and f indexes facilities owned by firm F . Our CEJP measure is the percentage share of these groups in the total human health risks generated by air toxics releases from the firm’s facilities. To obtain this, we divide this score by the total RSEI score for the firm, as reported in the Toxic 100: CEJPrF ≡ RSEI ScorerF /RSEI ScoreF (3.2) CEJP is a purely distributional measure, in that it does not distinguish between a dis- proportionate share of a small total human health impact and a disproportionate share of a large total impact. We examine the relationship between the CEJP measure and total pollution impacts in Section 5. To assess whether the share of impacts accruing to specific population groups is “dis- proportionate,” we must choose an appropriate counterfactual to define a “proportionate” impact. The most straightforward benchmark for this purpose is the share of the group in the national population. In the 2000 Census, racial and ethnic minorities11 constituted 31.8 11We classify as minority all persons reporting either Hispanic for ethnicity or a response other than white 10 http://www.peri.umass.edu/toxic100/ percent of the U.S. population, and people living below the official poverty line were 12.9 percent. Alternative benchmarks for assessing disproportionality include the share of the group in the population of the specific regions—for example, states or metropolitan areas—in which the firm’s facilities are located, or their share in the firm’s labor force. A region- specific benchmark would be consistent with the view that the facility siting decisions of firms are often “within-region” choices, constrained by the desire to locate within a certain part of the country for ease of access to input or output markets [Pastor et al., 2001]. An employment-based benchmark would provide a rough gauge of the balance between “costs” and “benefits” to specific groups, sometimes invoked in discussions of the supposed “jobs-versus-environment” tradeoff. Both alternatives would apply different benchmarks to different firms, complicating the task of inter-firm comparisons. Our CEJP measure can be compared to these and other benchmarks. In the tables presented here, we report national population shares as the simplest, and for our purposes most robust, standard for comparison. It is also of interest to see how a specific firm compares with other firms. For this purpose, our tables also show group shares of human health hazards aggregated over all firms and facilities in the RSEI-GM database and aggregated over the universe of the large firms represented in the Toxic 100. For all firms, the share of minorities and the poor in 2005 were 34.8 percent and 15.3 percent, respectively (above their respective national population shares of 31.8 percent and 12.9 percent). The shares for the Toxic 100 firms were slightly lower than for all firms, but still above the shares of these groups in the national population. Inter-firm comparisons can also be made within specific industrial sectors. To illustrate, we report “best-in-class” and “worst-in-class” CEJP measures for firms in the plastics and oil refining sectors below. 3.2 Results Table 1 reports the CEJP minority measure for the top ten firms ranked on this basis from the firms in the Toxic 100. In all ten cases, more than half of the human health impacts resulting from the firm’s air toxics releases are borne by minority groups. Two of these firms— Exxon Mobil and Arcelor Mittal—also rank in the top ten of The Toxic 100 itself; in other words, they rank very high in total pollution burden as well as the share of the burden borne by minorities. In both cases, the main subgroup contributing to the large impact on minorities is blacks. In the case of Exxon Mobil, the black share of total human health impacts is 55.5 percent—the highest share of any firm in the Toxic 100. [INSERT TABLE 1 HERE] Looking at the bottom three lines in Table 1, we can compare group shares of health hazards for all firms in the Toxic 100 and the entire RSEI-GM database to their shares in for race. The breakout columns for blacks, Asians and Pacific Islanders, Native Americans refer to persons reporting exactly one race and non-Hispanic ethnicity. The breakout column for Hispanics may refer to people of any race. Because of the multiracial and other categories, the breakout columns do not sum to the total for minorities. 11 the U.S. population. Again, the disproportionate burden borne by blacks is evident: their share of the total pollution burden (18.1 percent) is more than 50 percent greater than their share of the national population (11.8 percent). In the case of Hispanics, Asian-Pacific islanders, and American Indians, their shares of the total pollution burden are somewhat below their shares of the national population. This is consistent with the finding of Ash and Fetter (2004) that within metropolitan statistical areas (MSAs), Hispanics tend to live in significantly more polluted neighborhoods than non-Hispanic whites, but that this effect is moderated in national-level data by the fact that they tend to live in MSAs that have less industrial toxic air pollution than the national average. In the case of blacks, by contrast, Ash and Fetter (2004) found that they not only live “on the wrong side of the environmental tracks” at the MSA level, but also are concentrated in MSAs with above-average industrial air toxics pollution. Table 2 reports the CEJP poverty measure, again for the top ten firms ranked on this basis from the Toxic 100. Not surprisingly, there is considerable overlap with Table 1: seven firms place in both lists. In the cases of the top two firms—National Oilwell Varco and Hess—the share of human health impacts borne by people living below the poverty line is more than double their share in the national population. Three firms that rank in the top ten by the CEJP poverty measure—Exxon Mobil, Arcelor Mittal, and Archer Daniels Midland—also rank in the top ten of the Toxic 100 itself. [INSERT TABLE 2 HERE] The Appendix Table presents these measures for all of the firms in the Toxic 100 universe, together with their Toxic 100 rank, number of TRI-reporting facilities, number of releases (that is, chemical-facility combinations), and total human health hazard (RSEI) score. The firms with the highest shares for Hispanics, Asian/Pacific Islanders, and Native Americans are, respectively, Freeport-McMoran Copper & Gold, Avery Dennison, and Northeast Utili- ties; in each case, the share of these subgroups in the firm’s human health impacts is more than three times their share in the national population. 3.3 Environmental justice performance at the facility level Two factors enter into a firm’s CEJP score. The first is the share of minority or poverty groups in the human health impacts of all its facilities, averaged over the number of facilities. The second is the extent to which its “dirtiest” facilities—that is, the facilities with the highest total RSEI scores—are located in places where these shares are higher (or lower) than average. To illustrate this point, we examine facility-level measures of environmental justice per- formance for Exxon Mobil, the corporation with the highest share of total impacts borne by blacks. Table 3 presents data for the firm’s top five facilities, ranked by RSEI scores, and for a composite of the fifty other Exxon Mobil facilities that contribute to the firm’s score. It is evident that the top two facilities, both of which are in Baton Rouge, Louisiana, drive the result for blacks. It is also noteworthy that the next two facilities, refineries in Baytown, Texas, and Torrance, California, both have exceptionally large shares of Hispanics and, in the case of Torrance, Asian/Pacific-islanders. 12 [INSERT TABLE 3 HERE] 4 Best and worst “in class” rankings This section investigates whether inter-firm differences in environmental justice performance persist within specific industrial sectors, taking as examples two particularly “dirty” sectors, the manufacture of plastics (and other synthetic materials) and oil refining. Because firms often are diversified—owning facilities in a number of different industrial sectors—we restrict the comparison to facilities in the sectors of interest. The TRI and RSEI data include SIC (Standard Industrial Classification) codes for each reporting facility; we use these to select the relevant set of facilities for each firm.12 Tables 4 and 5 report the CEJP scores for firms in the oil and plastics/synthetics sectors, respectively. To conserve space, we report scores only for firms whose total human health hazard from air emissions from facilities in the relevant sector surpass a threshold level.13 The firms are ranked from “best-in-class” to “worst-in-class” on the basis of the share of human health impacts borne by minority groups.14 In the case of the oil industry, Tesoro, Marathon Oil, and Sunoco achieve best-in-class rankings, with minorities accounting for less than 35 percent of the impacts, although Tesoro is the only ranked firm whose minority share of health impacts is below the minority share in the U.S. population at large (31.8 percent). The worst-in-class rankings go to Pasadena Refining, ExxonMobil, and Hess: minorities account for more than 67 percent of the impacts from their oil-refining facilities. [INSERT TABLE 4 HERE] In the case of the plastics and synthetic materials sector, Neville Chemical Co., Eastman Chemical, and High Voltage Engineering Corporation achieve best-in-class rankings, with minorities accounting for less than 12 percent of the impacts. The worst-in-class rankings in this sector go to BP, ExxonMobil, and Resinall Corporation, with minorities accounting for more than 60 percent of the impacts. [INSERT TABLE 5 HERE] 5 Total Human Health Impact and CEJP The relationship between corporate environmental performance (CEP), here measured in terms of total human health impact from air toxics emissions at facilities owned by the firm, and corporate environmental justice performance (CEJP) is of interest for three reasons. First, if the correlation between these two dimensions of performance were extremely high—that is, the biggest polluters also had the biggest shares of minorities and the poor in 12Oil-refining facilities correspond to three-digit SIC code 291; plastics and synthetic materials manufac- turing facilities correspond to four-digit SIC codes 2820–2824. Some facilities engage in production activities in multiple industrial sectors, for which they can report up to six SIC codes. We select all facilities that report production in the relevant codes. 13As a cutoff, we use a combined RSEI score of 5,000 for the relevant facilities. 14Rankings based on the share borne by people with incomes below the poverty line (reported in the last column of the tables) yield similar results. 13 the resulting health impacts—then the calculation of a separate CEJP measure might not be worth the effort: CEP would tell us all we need to know. Second, there are plausible a priori reasons to expect that the correlation between the two will be positive, albeit imperfect. The reason is that where inequalities of power and wealth between polluters and the “pollutees” who bear environmental costs are larger, one outcome is likely to be a larger overall magnitude of pollution. Wealth inequalities can yield this result under the standard assumptions of benefit-cost analysis, in which the value of an adverse health impact is measured in terms of a person’s willingness to pay to avoid it. To put matters bluntly, in this calculus the health and lives of the poor are worth less than those of the rich. Where the society’s decisions about environmental policies are shaped by political influ- ence, in addition to benefit-cost calculations, power inequalities can further contribute to this outcome. For example, Boyce [2002] has suggested that environmental policies are governed by a “power-weighted social decision rule,” in which what matters is not only the monetary values of costs and benefits but also the power of the parties to whom these accrue. The relationship between CEP and CEJP can provide one test of this hypothesis. A final reason why this relationship is worth examining is that if, instead of a positive correlation, the two were inversely related—such that disproportional impacts were concen- trated among relatively minor polluters—then this might mitigate, to some degree, findings of environmental injustice. To examine this relationship, we looked at plotted total RSEI scores against our CEJP measures for the firms appearing in The Toxic 100. The results are shown in Figures 1 and 2 for the CEJP minority and poverty measures, respectively. In both cases, the results show a weak positive relationship, consistent with the expectation that the overall magnitude of pollution will be correlated with the distribution of the resulting burdens, but not so strongly correlated as to obviate the need for measures of the latter. [INSERT FIGURES 1 & 2 HERE] Fitting linear regression lines to the 100 observations in each figure, we find that as the minority share rises from 0 to 80 percent, the extent of observed variation, the predicted human health hazard rises by 27 percent. As the poverty share rises from 0 to 30 percent, the small range of variation in poverty shares, the predicted human health hazard rises by 150 percent. 6 Conclusions The measure of corporate environmental justice performance (CEJP) presented in this paper provides meaningful new information on an important dimension of corporate behavior. For ethical reasons, it is of interest to know not only how much pollution is released by a firm’s industrial facilities, but also how the resulting human health impacts are distributed across racial, ethnic, and income groups. The CEJP measure provides this information. Apart from ethical concerns, there may be good legal and financial reasons for corpora- tions and investors to pay attention to this dimension of firm performance. Environmental 14 justice—defined in terms of both race/ethnicity and income class—became an explicit objec- tive in federal government policy making in 1994, when President Clinton signed Executive Order 12898 directing each government agency to take steps to identify and rectify “dis- proportionately high and adverse human health or environmental effects of its programs, policies, and activities on minority populations and low-income populations.” In the case of minorities, moreover, systematically disproportionate burdens could prove to be grounds for legal challenges under the U.S. Civil Rights Act. Public and private responses could translate environmental injustice into liabilities that affect the firm’s bottom line. Regular measurement of CEJP can provide stakeholders—investors, managers, regula- tors, consumers, and residents of affected communities—with a report card for assessing levels and changes in performance. Furthermore, because the fate-and-dispersion model can be used to estimate concentrations from hypothetical releases, it can be used to predict the environmental and EJ impacts of planned expansions or decreases in air toxics emissions. The CEJP measure is scalable, and as we demonstrated above, it can be used to compare both firms and facilities within firms. It can be readily extended to specific industrial sectors, specific chemicals, or other classifications of industrial point-source pollution. We believe that the joint measurement of total impact (CEP) and disparate impacts (CEJP) provides the most robust picture of corporate environmental performance. Al- though correlated, neither measure adequately conveys information about the other. Both dimensions are relevant, and both should—and can—be incorporated into the assessment of corporate behavior. References Michael Ash and T. Robert Fetter. Who Lives on the Wrong Side of the Environmental Tracks? Social Science Quarterly, 85(2):441–462, 2004. Nicolaas W. Bouwes, Steven Hassur, and Marc Shapiro. Information for Empowerment: The EPA’s Risk-Screening Environmental Indicators Project. In James K. Boyce and Barry G. Shelley, editors, Natural Assets: Democratizing Environmental Ownership, pages 135–150. Washington, DC: Island Press, 2003. James K. Boyce. The Political Economy of the Environment. Edward Elgar, 2002. James K. Boyce. Inequality and Environmental Protection. In Jean-Marie Baland, Pranab Bardhan, and Samuel Bowles, editors, Inequality, Collective Action, and Environmental Sustainability, pages 314–348. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2007. Dave Bryan. Minority Groups Mobilize on Pollution: Alabama Towns Battle for PCB Cleanup Reflects Fight Against ‘Environmental Racism’. Associated Press, 6 April 2003. http://www.ejrc.cau.edu/washpostejarticle.html. J. Chakraborty and M. P. Armstrong. Exploring the use of buffer analysis for the identifica- tion of impacted areas in environmental equity assessment. Cartography and Geographic Information Systems, 24(3):145–157, 1997. 15 http://www.ejrc.cau.edu/washpostejarticle.html Paul Mohai and Robin Saha. Racial Inequality in the Distribution of Hazardous Waste: A National-Level Reassessment. Social Problems, 54(3):343–370, 2007. Office of Pollution Prevention and Toxics. Risk-Screening Environmental Indicators. U.S. Environmental Protection Agency, Washington, DC, 2004. Accessed February 1, 2008. URL: http://www.epa.gov/oppt/rsei. Manuel Pastor, James Sadd, and John Hipp. Which Came First? Toxic Facilities, Minority Move-in, and Environmental Justice. Journal of Urban Affairs, 23(1), 2001. Manuel Pastor, James Sadd, and Rachel Morello-Frosch. The Air is Always Cleaner on the Other Side: Race, Space, and Air Toxics Exposures in California. Journal of Urban Affairs, 27(2), 2006. Robin Saha and Paul Mohai. Historical Context and Hazardous Waste Facility Siting: Un- derstanding Temporal Patterns in Michigan. Social Problems, 2005. U.S. Senate Committee on Appropriations. PCB Contamination in Anniston, Al- abama. 107th Congress, 19 April 2002. Available at http://www.ewg.org/files/ AnnistonSenateHearingTrans.pdf. 16 http://www.epa.gov/oppt/rsei http://www.ewg.org/files/AnnistonSenateHearingTrans.pdf http://www.ewg.org/files/AnnistonSenateHearingTrans.pdf Figure 1. Total Human Health Impact and CEJP for Minorities: Toxic 100 ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ●● ● ●●●● ●●● ● ●● ● ● ●●● ●●● ● ● ●●●● ● ● ●● ●●● ●●● ●● ●● ●● ●● ●●●● ●●● ●●● ● ●● ● ●● ●● ●● ●●● ● ●● ●● ● ● ● ●●●● ●● ● 0 20 40 60 80 0 5 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 1 5 0 0 0 0 2 0 0 0 0 0 2 5 0 0 0 0 Minority Share S co re E.I. du Pont de Nemours Archer Daniels Midland (ADM) Dow Chemical Bayer Group Eastman Kodak General Electric Arcelor Mittal US Steel ExxonMobil AK Steel Holding Eastman Chemical Source: Toxic 100 Corporate RSEI Score and Appendix Table 1. 17 Figure 2. Total Human Health Impact and CEJP for Poverty: Toxic 100 ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ● ●● ● ● ● ●●● ●●● ●●● ● ● ●● ●● ●●● ●● ●●● ●● ●●● ● ●●●● ●●●●●● ●● ●● ●●●●● ●●● ● ● ●●● ●● ● ●● ●● ●● ●●● ●● ●●● ●●● ●●●● ●●● 0 20 40 60 80 0 5 0 0 0 0 1 0 0 0 0 0 1 5 0 0 0 0 2 0 0 0 0 0 2 5 0 0 0 0 Poor Share S co re E.I. du Pont de Nemours Archer Daniels Midland (ADM) Dow Chemical Bayer Group Eastman Kodak General Electric Arcelor Mittal US Steel ExxonMobil AK Steel Holding Eastman Chemical Source: Toxic 100 Corporate RSEI Score and Appendix Table 1. 18 Table 1. Corporate Environmental Justice Performance: Minorities Minority Black Hispanic Asian/Pacific Nat. Am. Share Share Share Share Share National Oilwell Varco 78.0 22.3 53.0 2.0 0.7 ExxonMobil 69.1 55.5 10.4 2.2 0.3 General Dynamics 69.0 11.1 49.1 6.7 1.0 Hess 66.5 15.6 47.6 4.9 0.3 Freeport-McMoran Copper & Gold 62.1 2.9 57.1 0.5 1.6 Arcelor Mittal 61.6 46.6 12.5 1.3 0.3 Valero Energy 59.9 38.7 18.3 1.8 0.5 Akzo Nobel 58.6 44.4 10.4 2.4 0.3 Public Service Enterprise Group (PSEG) 57.0 18.2 26.8 10.1 0.4 Northrop Grumman 56.6 49.8 3.3 1.8 0.4 Toxic 100 Firms 34.2 19.8 10.5 2.1 0.5 All Firms 34.8 18.1 12.6 2.2 0.6 US Population 31.8 11.8 13.7 3.7 0.7 19 Table 2. Corporate Environmental Justice Performance: People in Poverty Poor Share National Oilwell Varco 26.5 Hess 26.4 ExxonMobil 25.4 Akzo Nobel 25.2 Arcelor Mittal 24.9 Northrop Grumman 22.6 Archer Daniels Midland (ADM) 22.5 Rowan Cos. 21.6 Nucor 21.2 General Dynamics 20.9 Toxic 100 Firms 15.2 All Firms 15.3 US Population 12.9 20 Table 3. Minority and Poverty Shares of Airborne Human Health Risk: ExxonMobil Facilities Minority Black Hispanic Asian/Pacific Nat. Am. Poor Score Share Share Share Share Share Share Baton Rouge Refinery (LA) 62269 78.0 75.3 1.1 1.0 0.1 31.1 Baton Rouge Chemical (LA) 24748 73.1 70.0 1.2 1.1 0.1 29.1 Baytown Refinery (TX) 18405 54.6 15.0 35.8 2.6 0.5 15.3 Torrance Refinery (CA) 6710 69.9 10.8 40.9 15.5 0.7 15.1 Joliet Refinery (IL) 6277 33.7 16.5 13.0 2.9 0.2 7.8 50 Additional Facilities 10347 50.8 23.2 23.4 2.6 0.8 17.3 55 Total Facilities 128758 69.1 55.5 10.4 2.2 0.3 25.4 21 T ab le 4. M in or it y an d P ov er ty S h ar es of A ir b or n e H u m an H ea lt h R is k: O il R efi n in g M in or it y B la ck H is p an ic A si an /P ac ifi c N at . A m . P oo r F ac il it ie s R el ea se s S co re S h ar e S h ar e S h ar e S h ar e S h ar e S h ar e E xx on M ob il 8 56 4 11 53 70 65 .5 51 .9 10 .2 2. 4 0. 3 24 .6 C on oc oP h il li p s 17 79 0 90 47 8 34 .8 19 .6 10 .6 2. 3 0. 9 15 .4 V al er o E n er gy 17 10 31 83 41 6 59 .8 38 .6 18 .3 1. 8 0. 5 19 .7 B P 6 38 6 48 84 1 56 .2 16 .4 32 .6 5. 8 0. 6 16 .3 C it go P et ro le u m C or p . 7 31 4 29 36 4 47 .8 28 .5 15 .7 2. 3 0. 4 19 .4 P as ad en a R efi n in g S ys te m In c. 1 36 25 29 1 73 .6 12 .6 57 .7 2. 4 0. 6 25 .1 S u n oc o 5 17 6 24 89 6 34 .0 22 .9 5. 8 3. 8 0. 3 16 .3 T es or o 6 31 5 24 64 0 24 .5 2. 6 11 .6 5. 9 1. 8 10 .0 S u n co r E n er gy 1 35 20 37 8 45 .3 6. 9 33 .6 2. 5 1. 3 12 .9 M ot iv a E nt er p ri se s L .L .C . 5 17 3 14 70 7 42 .2 35 .6 4. 1 1. 4 0. 3 16 .8 H es s 2 11 0 12 56 4 67 .4 14 .6 49 .8 4. 9 0. 3 26 .9 S in cl ai r O il C or p . 3 17 1 12 45 9 35 .3 18 .2 6. 8 1. 1 5. 3 20 .3 R oy al D u tc h S h el l 6 29 1 11 43 0 43 .5 8. 8 25 .5 6. 0 1. 0 12 .2 M ar at h on O il 7 36 4 11 27 7 33 .8 16 .3 13 .6 1. 9 0. 6 14 .3 C h ev ro n 7 43 2 55 84 66 .2 17 .4 31 .9 13 .3 0. 6 18 .9 A ll O il R efi n in g 16 3 68 36 55 52 98 51 .3 27 .9 18 .8 2. 9 0. 7 19 .0 A ll F ir m s 10 26 36 16 47 0 14 57 69 82 34 .8 18 .1 12 .6 2. 2 0. 6 15 .3 U S P op u la ti on − − − 31 .8 11 .8 13 .7 3. 7 0. 7 12 .9 22 T ab le 5. M in or it y an d P ov er ty S h ar es of A ir b or n e H u m an H ea lt h R is k: P la st ic s an d S yn th et ic M at er ia ls M in or it y B la ck H is p an ic A si an /P ac ifi c N at . A m . P oo r F ac il it ie s R el ea se s S co re S h ar e S h ar e S h ar e S h ar e S h ar e S h ar e E .I . d u P on t d e N em ou rs 25 73 2 22 22 29 37 .1 31 .6 2. 8 1. 0 0. 3 17 .9 E as tm an C h em ic al 4 25 2 98 29 2 9. 9 6. 4 1. 7 0. 6 0. 2 15 .1 A p ol lo M gt . (H ex io n S p ec ia lt y C h em .) 23 37 0 62 76 6 40 .3 14 .8 22 .1 2. 1 0. 5 13 .2 D ow C h em ic al 23 11 81 62 80 6 43 .4 17 .1 23 .9 1. 3 0. 4 15 .0 N ev il le C h em ic al C o. 1 22 28 49 8 7. 6 4. 9 0. 6 1. 2 0. 1 6. 6 E xx on M ob il 9 28 9 26 77 0 71 .7 66 .3 3. 4 1. 2 0. 2 28 .3 B A S F 13 14 0 22 57 9 31 .3 22 .8 4. 7 1. 4 0. 4 13 .0 In vi st a S . A . R . L . 7 10 6 17 58 0 26 .5 20 .1 3. 8 0. 6 0. 5 13 .7 B P 2 20 3 14 86 4 77 15 .0 44 .3 15 .4 0. 8 20 .6 Z eo n C h em ic al s L P 2 23 14 75 9 17 11 .5 2. 1 1. 6 0. 2 8. 7 R es in al l C or p . 2 21 14 15 0 62 .5 60 .2 1. 2 0. 3 0. 4 32 .3 G en er al E le ct ri c 8 22 5 12 54 1 10 5. 6 2. 0 1. 0 0. 2 11 .5 S te p an C o. 1 25 12 34 5 35 .1 18 .2 12 .8 2. 8 0. 2 8. 2 G eo rg ia G u lf C or p . 3 13 5 11 13 8 45 .7 41 .7 1. 8 1. 3 0. 3 22 .5 C yt ec In d u st ri es In c. 7 10 8 10 95 7 12 .3 6. 0 3. 2 1. 1 0. 5 14 .1 L an xe ss 3 43 10 54 9 17 .4 11 .7 2. 8 1. 5 0. 2 9. 9 L u b ri zo l C or p . 8 14 7 10 21 1 21 .1 14 .7 2. 7 1. 7 0. 3 12 .7 R oy al D u tc h S h el l 1 63 88 24 48 .2 10 .3 34 .2 2. 7 0. 5 13 .0 U . S . P ol ym er s A cc u re z L L C 1 10 83 97 24 .8 17 .6 3. 0 1. 6 0. 4 18 .3 R oh m an d H aa s 14 32 3 79 55 25 .1 17 .1 2. 7 3. 6 0. 3 21 .3 H er cu le s In c. 5 32 73 66 40 .2 21 .5 15 .3 1. 7 0. 5 20 .8 M it su b is h i C h em ic al 2 20 69 06 20 .8 12 .5 4. 3 2. 6 0. 2 10 .6 H ig h V ol ta ge E n gi n ee ri n g C or p . 1 4 65 55 11 .2 3. 0 5. 5 1. 9 0. 2 6. 2 W it co C or p . 2 62 65 53 38 .8 34 .5 2. 3 1. 1 0. 2 16 .9 W es tl ak e O le fi n s C or p . 4 42 63 52 38 .3 34 .1 2. 0 1. 2 0. 2 16 .5 S ol u ti a In c. 5 72 63 36 29 20 .5 5. 6 0. 9 0. 9 15 .2 G oo d ye ar 2 30 61 85 58 .6 20 .7 33 .7 3. 3 0. 4 18 .5 M ic h el in G ro u p 1 17 54 36 35 .5 31 .5 1. 5 0. 7 0. 2 17 .0 In n ov en e U S A L L C 3 69 54 04 24 .1 19 .1 1. 9 0. 6 0. 2 16 .7 A ll P la st ic s 54 3 88 98 84 74 04 34 .1 22 .6 8. 3 1. 6 0. 3 16 .0 A ll F ir m s 10 26 36 16 47 0 14 57 69 82 34 .8 18 .1 12 .6 2. 2 0. 6 15 .3 U S P op u la ti on − − − 31 .8 11 .8 13 .7 3. 7 0. 7 12 .9 23 A p p e n d ix T a b le 1 . M in o ri ty a n d P o v e rt y S h a re s o f A ir b o rn e H u m a n H e a lt h R is k : T o x ic 1 0 0 C o rp o ra ti o n s T o x ic 1 0 0 R S E I M in o ri ty B la ck H is p a n ic A si a n / P a c ifi c N a t. A m . P o o r R a n k F a c il it ie s R e le a se s S c o re S h a re S h a re S h a re S h a re S h a re S h a re E .I . d u P o n t d e N e m o u rs 1 5 8 1 2 7 7 2 8 5 6 6 1 3 6 .0 2 9 .9 3 .4 1 .0 0 .4 1 7 .3 A rc h e r D a n ie ls M id la n d (A D M ) 2 3 4 2 1 1 2 1 3 1 5 9 3 2 .0 2 5 .9 2 .7 1 .1 0 .2 2 2 .5 D o w C h e m ic a l 3 4 1 1 4 1 5 1 8 9 6 7 3 4 2 .7 1 5 .0 2 3 .6 2 .8 0 .4 1 3 .0 B a y e r G ro u p 4 1 6 2 8 9 1 7 2 7 7 3 2 4 .3 3 .2 1 8 .5 1 .4 0 .4 6 .8 E a st m a n K o d a k 5 6 1 4 2 1 6 2 4 3 0 2 6 .2 1 4 .2 8 .2 2 .0 0 .3 1 3 .4 G e n e ra l E le c tr ic 6 1 3 0 8 2 8 1 4 9 0 6 1 3 2 .4 1 1 .7 1 6 .1 2 .7 0 .5 1 3 .4 A rc e lo r M it ta l 7 2 4 3 0 4 1 3 4 5 7 3 6 1 .6 4 6 .6 1 2 .5 1 .3 0 .3 2 4 .9 U S S te e l 8 1 2 2 8 1 1 2 9 1 2 3 3 6 .8 2 9 .3 4 .6 0 .9 0 .4 1 7 .8 E x x o n M o b il 9 5 5 1 4 5 2 1 2 8 7 5 8 6 9 .1 5 5 .5 1 0 .4 2 .2 0 .3 2 5 .4 A K S te e l H o ld in g 1 0 9 1 2 4 1 0 1 4 2 8 7 .9 5 .0 0 .9 0 .7 0 .2 1 6 .9 E a st m a n C h e m ic a l 1 1 5 2 8 4 9 8 4 3 2 9 .9 6 .4 1 .7 0 .6 0 .2 1 5 .1 D u k e E n e rg y 1 2 2 2 4 1 0 9 3 1 7 4 2 0 .3 1 4 .7 2 .9 1 .5 0 .3 9 .8 C o n o c o P h il li p s 1 3 4 5 1 2 6 9 9 1 9 9 3 3 4 .7 1 9 .6 1 0 .4 2 .5 0 .9 1 5 .2 P re c is io n C a st p a rt s 1 4 2 9 1 9 5 8 7 5 0 0 1 5 .8 5 .0 5 .3 2 .7 0 .6 1 2 .8 A lc o a 1 5 6 1 5 7 4 8 5 9 8 3 2 0 .3 1 1 .1 5 .2 1 .5 1 .2 1 1 .7 V a le ro E n e rg y 1 6 3 6 1 4 4 2 8 3 9 9 3 5 9 .9 3 8 .7 1 8 .3 1 .8 0 .5 1 9 .8 F o rd M o to r 1 7 3 5 4 4 4 7 5 3 6 0 2 4 .6 1 5 .4 5 .1 2 .0 0 .3 1 1 .2 G e n e ra l M o to rs 1 8 4 5 6 6 2 7 3 2 4 8 2 9 .5 1 7 .9 7 .3 1 .7 0 .4 1 5 .6 G o o d y e a r 1 9 2 7 2 1 1 6 7 6 3 2 2 7 .3 1 9 .1 4 .3 1 .6 0 .4 1 5 .7 E .O N 2 0 1 0 1 9 4 6 5 5 7 9 2 1 .6 1 7 .1 1 .8 1 .1 0 .2 1 3 .2 M a ts u sh it a E le c tr ic In d l 2 1 4 1 8 6 5 3 4 6 5 4 .6 4 8 .1 3 .6 1 .4 0 .3 1 3 .1 F re e p o rt -M c M o ra n C o p p e r & G o ld 2 2 1 8 1 6 8 6 3 9 1 1 6 2 .1 2 .9 5 7 .1 0 .5 1 .6 1 4 .8 A p o ll o M g t. (H e x io n S p e c ia lt y C h e m ic a ls ) 2 3 3 5 4 2 3 6 3 8 8 0 4 0 .2 1 4 .9 2 1 .9 2 .1 0 .6 1 3 .3 A v e ry D e n n is o n 2 4 1 3 1 0 2 6 2 7 4 0 3 7 .7 8 .3 1 4 .4 1 2 .7 0 .2 9 .7 B A S F 2 5 4 5 6 0 3 6 0 9 8 4 3 1 .9 2 4 .5 4 .3 1 .1 0 .3 1 5 .9 O w e n s C o rn in g 2 6 3 7 1 4 3 5 9 6 0 9 4 2 .6 1 4 .2 2 2 .0 4 .4 0 .5 1 4 .2 D o m in io n R e so u rc e s 2 7 1 9 1 9 6 5 8 6 4 2 2 9 .3 2 1 .4 3 .5 2 .2 0 .3 1 1 .3 A ll e g h e n y T e ch n o lo g ie s 2 8 2 9 1 6 8 5 8 3 7 5 8 .3 5 .2 1 .2 0 .6 0 .2 1 3 .1 B P 2 9 5 8 1 2 7 1 5 4 3 3 6 5 4 .7 1 6 .9 3 0 .9 5 .4 0 .7 1 6 .2 H o n e y w e ll In te rn a ti o n a l 3 0 5 7 4 1 1 5 0 4 1 7 4 2 .1 3 0 .3 8 .8 1 .9 0 .3 1 5 .8 In te rn a ti o n a l P a p e r 3 1 5 2 6 0 8 4 9 3 8 5 3 0 .6 2 5 .5 2 .6 1 .0 0 .4 1 6 .2 A sh la n d 3 2 6 7 6 4 6 4 3 4 9 2 3 0 .7 2 0 .6 5 .9 1 .6 0 .3 1 8 .9 C o n st e ll a ti o n E n e rg y 3 3 1 4 1 0 8 4 2 9 7 2 3 5 .5 2 1 .5 1 0 .2 2 .1 0 .3 1 1 .2 P u b li c S e rv ic e E n te rp ri se G ro u p (P S E G ) 3 4 9 9 7 4 1 7 7 3 5 7 .0 1 8 .2 2 6 .8 1 0 .1 0 .4 1 6 .5 A E S 3 5 1 4 1 9 1 3 9 7 8 9 2 9 .8 1 4 .0 1 3 .9 1 .2 0 .3 1 5 .1 P ro g re ss E n e rg y 3 6 1 4 2 3 4 3 8 0 2 7 2 4 .0 1 2 .3 7 .7 2 .1 0 .6 1 1 .2 N u c o r 3 7 2 9 3 1 7 3 6 9 6 3 5 1 .3 4 6 .9 2 .6 0 .7 0 .3 2 1 .2 U n it e d T e ch n o lo g ie s 3 8 4 2 1 5 0 3 6 5 2 6 3 0 .6 2 1 .7 5 .7 2 .0 0 .3 7 .6 T im k e n 3 9 1 5 7 9 3 6 0 4 7 1 7 .6 1 2 .9 1 .1 0 .5 0 .4 1 7 .4 B e rk sh ir e H a th a w a y 4 0 6 2 4 1 9 3 5 2 8 5 3 7 .8 2 4 .3 1 0 .1 1 .5 0 .7 1 3 .2 S P X 4 1 1 2 4 9 3 4 5 5 9 3 9 .8 1 9 .6 1 4 .6 3 .2 0 .5 1 1 .2 T o x ic 1 0 0 F ir m s − 2 5 1 8 3 0 9 6 5 4 7 2 4 0 9 4 3 4 .2 1 9 .8 1 0 .5 2 .1 0 .5 1 5 .2 A ll F ir m s − 1 0 2 6 3 6 1 6 4 7 0 1 4 5 7 6 9 8 2 3 4 .8 1 8 .1 1 2 .6 2 .2 0 .6 1 5 .3 U S P o p u la ti o n − − − − 3 1 .8 1 1 .8 1 3 .7 3 .7 0 .7 1 2 .9 24 A p p e n d ix T a b le 1 , c o n ti n u e d . M in o ri ty a n d P o v e rt y S h a re s o f A ir b o rn e H u m a n H e a lt h R is k : T o x ic 1 0 0 C o rp o ra ti o n s T o x ic 1 0 0 R S E I M in o ri ty B la ck H is p a n ic A si a n / P a c ifi c N a t. A m . P o o r R a n k F a c il it ie s R e le a se s S c o re S h a re S h a re S h a re S h a re S h a re S h a re R o y a l D u tc h S h e ll 4 2 1 9 6 0 9 3 4 5 5 6 4 3 .5 1 7 .3 2 0 .4 3 .8 0 .7 1 3 .8 S o u th e rn C o 4 3 2 2 3 0 6 3 3 5 7 7 3 3 .6 2 6 .2 4 .2 1 .7 0 .4 1 2 .5 A ll e g h e n y E n e rg y 4 4 9 1 5 9 3 1 5 3 9 1 0 .2 7 .1 0 .8 1 .0 0 .2 1 4 .1 A m e ri c a n E le c tr ic 4 5 2 0 5 2 4 3 1 3 6 4 9 .3 5 .7 1 .2 0 .7 0 .4 1 2 .4 R e li a n t E n e rg y 4 6 1 5 2 6 0 3 0 8 2 1 1 4 .0 8 .1 3 .5 1 .2 0 .2 1 0 .7 B o e in g 4 7 1 2 1 1 3 3 0 4 5 3 3 3 .7 1 2 .3 1 1 .1 6 .1 1 .3 1 3 .6 G e n e ra l D y n a m ic s 4 8 1 6 6 7 3 0 3 3 7 6 9 .0 1 1 .1 4 9 .1 6 .7 1 .0 2 0 .9 O c c id e n ta l P e tr o le u m 4 9 2 1 3 9 1 3 0 1 6 7 4 3 .6 3 0 .8 9 .7 1 .6 0 .4 1 6 .9 K e y S p a n 5 0 4 4 0 2 9 0 0 8 5 3 .7 1 8 .2 2 4 .7 9 .1 0 .5 1 7 .8 L y o n d e ll C h e m ic a l 5 1 2 5 5 0 1 2 8 5 9 1 3 3 .6 1 1 .8 1 8 .5 1 .9 0 .3 1 4 .9 S u n o c o 5 2 4 0 7 7 4 2 7 8 5 1 3 3 .5 2 2 .2 6 .1 3 .6 0 .3 1 6 .6 A n h e u se r- B u sc h C o s 5 3 2 1 7 9 2 7 0 3 2 4 1 .0 3 0 .1 6 .5 2 .4 0 .4 1 6 .7 B a ll 5 4 3 0 1 8 4 2 5 7 0 9 3 8 .5 1 1 .3 2 1 .4 4 .1 0 .6 1 4 .8 D e e re & C o 5 5 1 0 6 7 2 5 3 4 6 1 9 .9 6 .8 1 0 .2 1 .1 0 .4 1 5 .6 P ro c te r & G a m b le 5 6 2 3 1 0 8 2 5 2 3 8 4 1 .2 3 6 .6 2 .4 1 .1 0 .2 1 6 .1 T e so ro 5 7 8 3 6 1 2 4 7 0 8 2 4 .6 2 .6 1 1 .6 5 .9 1 .8 1 0 .0 T e m p le -I n la n d 5 8 1 9 1 2 0 2 4 5 3 7 4 7 .0 2 4 .8 2 1 .2 0 .5 0 .4 2 0 .1 P fi z e r 5 9 1 7 2 3 1 2 4 5 0 8 3 8 .3 1 9 .5 1 3 .9 2 .5 0 .5 1 9 .8 R o w a n C o s. 6 0 2 2 1 2 4 3 8 9 4 6 .2 3 0 .3 1 3 .6 0 .7 0 .5 2 1 .6 L e g g e tt & P la tt 6 1 3 6 6 9 2 3 8 7 0 2 8 .2 5 .5 1 8 .6 1 .8 1 .0 1 2 .6 N o rt h ro p G ru m m a n 6 2 1 4 8 7 2 3 7 9 8 5 6 .6 4 9 .8 3 .3 1 .8 0 .4 2 2 .6 W e y e rh a e u se r 6 3 4 9 4 7 6 2 2 7 0 8 2 3 .0 1 5 .1 4 .0 1 .1 1 .1 1 7 .1 R o h m a n d H a a s 6 4 3 7 5 8 4 2 2 4 8 9 4 0 .9 1 5 .1 2 1 .4 3 .1 0 .4 1 6 .5 T y c o In te rn a ti o n a l 6 5 2 9 2 1 5 2 2 1 1 5 3 2 .7 1 6 .6 1 0 .6 3 .0 0 .7 9 .3 T e re x 6 6 1 1 3 1 2 1 7 3 0 1 7 .3 4 .9 4 .6 4 .4 0 .6 9 .4 C o rn in g 6 7 6 2 6 2 0 9 4 2 1 7 .6 1 2 .6 2 .4 1 .2 0 .3 1 2 .6 E x e lo n 6 8 5 5 3 2 0 8 1 1 3 3 .6 2 4 .2 4 .9 3 .3 0 .2 1 3 .6 F o rt u n e B ra n d s 6 9 2 2 1 0 3 2 0 5 8 3 1 9 .5 8 .0 9 .4 0 .8 0 .5 8 .0 F ir st E n e rg y 7 0 7 1 5 8 2 0 4 4 1 1 6 .8 1 2 .7 1 .7 1 .1 0 .1 1 0 .0 S u n c o r E n e rg y 7 1 1 3 5 2 0 3 7 8 4 5 .3 6 .9 3 3 .6 2 .5 1 .3 1 2 .9 C ro w n H o ld in g s 7 2 2 3 1 3 7 1 9 4 4 7 3 0 .5 8 .0 1 7 .9 3 .6 0 .5 1 4 .3 M a sc o 7 3 3 4 1 4 8 1 8 5 7 2 6 .7 1 .3 2 .8 1 .4 0 .4 1 2 .0 T h y ss e n K ru p p G ro u p 7 4 1 6 1 3 0 1 8 1 3 3 2 1 .7 1 2 .0 7 .3 1 .2 0 .5 1 2 .1 T e x tr o n 7 5 1 3 6 9 1 7 4 4 3 3 3 .6 2 4 .5 4 .9 1 .6 0 .7 1 3 .6 S o n y 7 6 6 3 6 1 6 4 2 6 1 2 .5 7 .4 2 .1 2 .0 0 .2 5 .3 M ir a n t 7 7 9 1 3 8 1 6 3 3 7 4 2 .4 2 4 .9 1 0 .6 4 .6 0 .4 9 .2 R A G 7 8 3 1 2 5 2 1 6 0 8 0 5 2 .9 4 5 .6 4 .2 1 .5 0 .5 1 8 .4 A lc a n 7 9 1 1 5 1 1 5 2 3 1 1 0 .8 6 .6 2 .2 0 .6 0 .2 1 2 .1 H u n ts m a n 8 0 1 7 2 8 0 1 5 1 1 9 4 7 .7 3 5 .0 9 .3 2 .2 0 .4 2 0 .4 B ri d g e st o n e 8 1 3 0 1 5 5 1 4 9 5 2 1 5 .9 8 .7 4 .0 1 .5 0 .4 1 0 .1 D a n a h e r 8 2 2 2 4 6 1 4 6 2 1 2 3 .9 3 .9 1 5 .8 2 .1 0 .9 1 5 .7 T o x ic 1 0 0 F ir m s − 2 5 1 8 3 0 9 6 5 4 7 2 4 0 9 4 3 4 .2 1 9 .8 1 0 .5 2 .1 0 .5 1 5 .2 A ll F ir m s − 1 0 2 6 3 6 1 6 4 7 0 1 4 5 7 6 9 8 2 3 4 .8 1 8 .1 1 2 .6 2 .2 0 .6 1 5 .3 U S P o p u la ti o n − − − − 3 1 .8 1 1 .8 1 3 .7 3 .7 0 .7 1 2 .9 25 A p p e n d ix T a b le 1 , c o n ti n u e d . M in o ri ty a n d P o v e rt y S h a re s o f A ir b o rn e H u m a n H e a lt h R is k : T o x ic 1 0 0 C o rp o ra ti o n s T o x ic 1 0 0 R S E I M in o ri ty B la ck H is p a n ic A si a n / P a c ifi c N a t. A m . P o o r R a n k F a c il it ie s R e le a se s S c o re S h a re S h a re S h a re S h a re S h a re S h a re P P G In d u st ri e s 8 3 3 0 4 9 6 1 4 3 0 0 2 3 .2 1 6 .7 3 .9 1 .1 0 .3 1 3 .0 H e ss 8 4 2 4 4 5 7 1 3 6 8 7 6 6 .5 1 5 .6 4 7 .6 4 .9 0 .3 2 6 .4 A k z o N o b e l 8 5 2 7 3 7 1 1 3 4 5 3 5 8 .6 4 4 .4 1 0 .4 2 .4 0 .3 2 5 .2 D y n e g y In c . 8 6 7 1 0 7 1 3 4 3 9 2 5 .6 1 3 .2 8 .9 2 .1 0 .3 1 0 .1 F e d e ra l- M o g u l 8 7 2 5 1 1 8 1 3 4 3 5 2 8 .0 2 1 .5 3 .5 1 .3 0 .3 1 3 .6 S ta n le y W o rk s 8 8 8 3 0 1 3 1 9 6 3 2 .1 2 3 .3 5 .7 1 .7 0 .4 1 0 .2 K o m a ts u 8 9 2 4 1 3 1 3 2 3 0 .9 2 3 .2 4 .0 1 .0 0 .3 1 9 .2 S a in t- G o b a in 9 0 5 5 1 5 9 1 3 0 1 2 3 8 .6 2 3 .5 1 0 .2 3 .0 0 .6 1 6 .7 P P L 9 1 4 8 3 1 2 9 7 2 1 1 .6 4 .3 4 .6 1 .6 0 .2 8 .0 C a te rp il la r 9 2 1 3 5 6 1 2 9 2 4 2 4 .2 1 1 .9 8 .6 1 .7 0 .2 1 1 .0 S m u rfi t- S to n e C o n ta in e r 9 3 3 0 2 4 4 1 2 8 6 8 2 9 .9 2 3 .1 3 .1 1 .6 0 .7 1 2 .0 S ie m e n s 9 4 2 2 6 6 1 2 6 4 9 3 2 .8 1 8 .3 1 0 .5 2 .1 0 .4 1 2 .8 M e a d W e st v a c o 9 5 1 0 2 1 4 1 2 4 6 5 4 0 .9 3 4 .0 4 .0 1 .4 0 .4 1 8 .3 M a ra th o n O il 9 6 3 7 7 0 5 1 2 4 5 4 3 3 .0 1 6 .3 1 2 .9 1 .9 0 .5 1 4 .3 E m e rs o n E le c tr ic 9 7 3 9 1 1 0 1 2 2 5 8 1 3 .1 7 .2 3 .7 0 .9 0 .3 1 5 .1 N o rt h e a st U ti li ti e s 9 8 5 8 4 1 1 1 1 5 1 1 .7 1 .4 5 .0 1 .4 3 .1 7 .9 N a ti o n a l O il w e ll V a rc o 9 9 7 2 5 1 1 0 4 2 7 8 .0 2 2 .3 5 3 .0 2 .0 0 .7 2 6 .5 D a n a 1 0 0 1 8 4 9 1 0 6 3 8 3 6 .2 2 9 .4 5 .3 0 .4 0 .2 1 7 .6 C h e v ro n 1 0 1 4 8 9 8 4 1 0 5 0 5 4 5 .4 1 7 .1 1 7 .0 8 .3 0 .4 1 3 .7 T o x ic 1 0 0 F ir m s − 2 5 1 8 3 0 9 6 5 4 7 2 4 0 9 4 3 4 .2 1 9 .8 1 0 .5 2 .1 0 .5 1 5 .2 A ll F ir m s − 1 0 2 6 3 6 1 6 4 7 0 1 4 5 7 6 9 8 2 3 4 .8 1 8 .1 1 2 .6 2 .2 0 .6 1 5 .3 U S P o p u la ti o n − − − − 3 1 .8 1 1 .8 1 3 .7 3 .7 0 .7 1 2 .9 26 Introduction Data and Methods The RSEI project The RSEI Project and Public-Release Data The RSEI Geographic Microdata (RSEI-GM) Census of Population & Housing: The Spatial Join Corporation-facility matching A Measure of Corporate Environmental Justice Performance Measuring group shares of human health risk Results Environmental justice performance at the facility level Best and worst ``in class'' rankings Total Human Health Impact and CEJP Conclusions work_f5wsakoncfae5per2cf3pumzjy ---- [PDF] Transgenerational epigenetics and environmental justice | Semantic Scholar Skip to search formSkip to main content> Semantic Scholar's Logo Search Sign InCreate Free Account You are currently offline. Some features of the site may not work correctly. DOI:10.1093/eep/dvx011 Corpus ID: 1428014Transgenerational epigenetics and environmental justice @article{Rothstein2017TransgenerationalEA, title={Transgenerational epigenetics and environmental justice}, author={M. Rothstein and H. Harrell and G. Marchant}, journal={Environmental Epigenetics}, year={2017}, volume={3} } M. Rothstein, H. Harrell, G. Marchant Published 2017 Political Science, Medicine Environmental Epigenetics Abstract Human transmission to offspring and future generations of acquired epigenetic modifications has not been definitively established, although there are several environmental exposures with suggestive evidence. This article uses three examples of hazardous substances with greater exposures in vulnerable populations: pesticides, lead, and diesel exhaust. It then considers whether, if there were scientific evidence of transgenerational epigenetic inheritance, there would be greater… Expand View on SSRN academic.oup.com Save to Library Create Alert Cite Launch Research Feed Share This Paper 15 CitationsBackground Citations 5 View All Topics from this paper study of epigenetics SEN virus Biological Science Disciplines substance Pesticides Greater Than responsibility Inheritance Patterns Hazardous Substances Diesel Fuel Policy 15 Citations Citation Type Citation Type All Types Cites Results Cites Methods Cites Background Has PDF Publication Type Author More Filters More Filters Filters Sort by Relevance Sort by Most Influenced Papers Sort by Citation Count Sort by Recency Transgenerational epigenetic inheritance and social responsibility: perspectives from the social sciences M. Meloni, R. Mueller Sociology, Medicine Environmental epigenetics 2018 11 PDF Save Alert Research Feed Human rights in the postgenomic era: Challenges and opportunities arising with epigenetics C. Dupras, Y. Joly, E. Rial-Sebbag Political Science 2020 1 View 1 excerpt, cites background Save Alert Research Feed Epigenetics, ethics, law and society: A multidisciplinary review of descriptive, instrumental, dialectical and reflexive analyses C. Dupras, Katie M. Saulnier, Y. Joly Psychology, Medicine Social studies of science 2019 8 Save Alert Research Feed Epigenetics: ethics, politics, biosociality L. Chiapperino Sociology, Medicine British medical bulletin 2018 4 PDF Save Alert Research Feed POHaD: why we should study future fathers Adelheid Soubry Psychology, Medicine Environmental epigenetics 2018 44 PDF Save Alert Research Feed Points-to-consider on the return of results in epigenetic research S. Dyke, Katie M. Saulnier, +8 authors Y. Joly Psychology, Medicine Genome Medicine 2019 10 Save Alert Research Feed Air pollution associated epigenetic modifications: Transgenerational inheritance and underlying molecular mechanisms. A. Shukla, N. Bunkar, +5 authors P. Mishra Biology, Medicine The Science of the total environment 2019 29 Save Alert Research Feed Epigenetics at the epicenter of a revolution in ARTs D. Albertini Medicine, Biology Journal of assisted reproduction and genetics 2018 PDF View 1 excerpt, cites background Save Alert Research Feed Impact of Environmental Injustice on Children’s Health—Interaction between Air Pollution and Socioeconomic Status Sahana Mathiarasan, Anke Hüls Medicine International journal of environmental research and public health 2021 PDF Save Alert Research Feed Synthetic female gonadal hormones alter neurodevelopmental programming and behavior in F1 offspring K. Garbett, T. Ding, J. Sweatt Biology, Medicine Hormones and Behavior 2020 View 2 excerpts, cites background Save Alert Research Feed ... 1 2 ... References SHOWING 1-10 OF 126 REFERENCES SORT BYRelevance Most Influenced Papers Recency DDT, epigenetic harm, and transgenerational environmental justice W. Kabasenche, M. Skinner Political Science, Medicine Environmental Health 2014 24 PDF View 2 excerpts, references background Save Alert Research Feed The ambiguous nature of epigenetic responsibility C. Dupras, V. Ravitsky Sociology, Medicine Journal of Medical Ethics 2016 24 PDF View 2 excerpts, references background Save Alert Research Feed Epigenetics and Future Generations. Lorenzo Del Savio, M. Loi, E. Stupka Sociology, Medicine Bioethics 2015 14 View 1 excerpt, references background Save Alert Research Feed Epigenetic inheritance and the responsibility for health in society. Mark Hanson, Ruth Müller Medicine The lancet. Diabetes & endocrinology 2017 15 View 1 excerpt, references background Save Alert Research Feed Multigenerational and transgenerational effects of endocrine disrupting chemicals: A role for altered epigenetic regulation? F. Xin, M. Susiarjo, M. Bartolomei Biology, Medicine Seminars in cell & developmental biology 2015 116 View 1 excerpt, references background Save Alert Research Feed Race and the new epigenetic biopolitics of environmental health B. Mansfield Biology 2012 78 Save Alert Research Feed Epigenetics in the Neoliberal "Regime of Truth": A Biopolitical Perspective on Knowledge Translation. C. Dupras, V. Ravitsky Sociology, Medicine The Hastings Center report 2016 18 View 1 excerpt, references background Save Alert Research Feed Neurological Diversity and Epigenetic Influences in Utero. An Ethical Investigation of Maternal Responsibility Towards the Future Child K. Hens Psychology 2017 3 Save Alert Research Feed Human transgenerational responses to early-life experience: potential impact on development, health and biomedical research M. Pembrey, R. Saffery, L. Bygren Biology, Medicine Journal of Medical Genetics 2014 197 PDF Save Alert Research Feed Social Epigenetics and Equality of Opportunity M. Loi, Lorenzo Del Savio, E. Stupka Sociology, Medicine Public health ethics 2013 74 PDF Save Alert Research Feed ... 1 2 3 4 5 ... Related Papers Abstract Topics 15 Citations 126 References Related Papers Stay Connected With Semantic Scholar Sign Up About Semantic Scholar Semantic Scholar is a free, AI-powered research tool for scientific literature, based at the Allen Institute for AI. Learn More → Resources DatasetsSupp.aiAPIOpen Corpus Organization About UsResearchPublishing PartnersData Partners   FAQContact Proudly built by AI2 with the help of our Collaborators Terms of Service•Privacy Policy The Allen Institute for AI By clicking accept or continuing to use the site, you agree to the terms outlined in our Privacy Policy, Terms of Service, and Dataset License ACCEPT & CONTINUE work_fammyzn6vfae7hnhguxmfauhnu ---- Violence and social justice Vittorio Bufacchi Palgrave MacMillan, Basingstoke, 2007, pp. xi, 218, hardcover £55.00, $32.95, ISBN: 0230552951 Contemporary Political Theory (2010) 9, 513–516. doi:10.1057/cpt.2010.13 ‘No justice, no peace’, threatens the bumper sticker and rally sign, raising in this popular form a serious question for contemporary political theory: What is the connection of violence and justice? Does injustice justify violence? Is violence, by its very nature, unjust? Vittorio Bufacchi attempts to clarify some of the conceptual puzzles surrounding our thinking about violence. Even if one demurs from some of his conclusions, the clear exposition of his liberal position makes this book a valuable contribution for political theorists trying to understand these critically important questions. Bufacchi offers a new definition of violence. He distinguishes between two common accounts of violence, which he labels the ‘minimalist approach’, which sees violence as an act of ‘intentional, excessive force’ and the ‘comprehensive approach’, in which violence is ‘a violation of rights’ (p. 26). The first of these approaches, Bufacchi argues, views violence more from the perspective of perpetrators, and the second, more from the perspective of victims. Arguing that the distinction between these two approaches is more ideological than logical, Bufacchi suggests his own alternative, as a way to provide an account of the nature of violence that ‘aspires to be universally valid’ (p. 29) and which can be seen to be from the perspective of a third-party observer. According to Bufacchi, then, violence is best understood as a ‘violation of integrity’, ‘used here in a strictly non-philosophical sense, meaning wholeness or intactness’ (p. 40). ‘An act of violence is fundamentally a violation of the integrity of the subject or object that suffers the violence, to the extent that the act of violence takes something away from the victim, therefore shattering the pre-existing psychological and/or physical unity that was in place before the violence took place’ (p. 46). For Bufacchi, this definition combines elements of both of the previous two understandings, but allows a third party to make the judgments about when violence has occurred. This allows him to identify four faces of violence: ‘when integrity is violated intentionally by means of a direct action; when integrity is violated intentionally by means of an omission; when the violation of integrity is foreseeable (even if not intended) as Book Reviews 513r 2010 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Vol. 9, 4, 508–516 a result of certain actions and when the violation of integrity is foreseeable (even if not intended) as a result of certain omissions’ (p. 91). From this definition of violence, through a series of elegant moves, Bufacchi is able to demonstrate that what is wrong about violence is that it results in humiliation, understanding humiliation as an affront to one’s integrity. By this account, then, Bufacchi defines violence as overlapping with the unjust. Bufacchi ends by considering whether violence can ever be just; he forces Fanon’s argument for violence into a kind of ‘identity’ argument for violence and finds it unconvincing, but argues that consequentialist accounts can help us to answer the question of ‘just violence’ by introducing a kind of proportionality. This short summary does not do justice to the intelligence of Bufacchi’s analysis; it is worth reading carefully. The most obvious target of Bufacchi’s argument is obviously and predictably approaches that see violence as ‘structural violence’. Bufacchi takes issue with this approach, begun with the Norwegian thinker Johan Galtung, whose more expansive definition is that ‘violence is present when human beings are being influenced so that their actual somatic and mental realizations are below their potential realizations’ (quoted at page 134) and for whom such structural violence is more harmful than direct violence. For Bufacchi, structural violence so broadens and weakens the category of violence as to make it meaningless; better, he argues, to call such exploitation ‘exploitation’ and not to assimilate it to the term violence. What, he asks, is gained by calling it violence? Quite the contrary, argues Bufacchi, expanding a term waters down its conceptual and moral force. Further, he argues, since some people see violence as biologically inevitable, then ‘if an injustice is reclassified as an act of violence, there is the potential risk that injustice will also be seen as inevitable’ (p. 137). ‘Fortunately’, he continues, ‘this debate between geneticists and philosophers can conveniently be by-passed if we rethink the relationship between injustice and violence y ’ (p. 137). Then, drawing upon the work of Judith Shklar, who saw injustice as so harmful that ‘most of us would rather reorder reality than admit that we are the helpless objects of injustice’ (p. 139), Bufacchi observes that the harm of injustice is that it, like violence, is bad and wrong because of ‘the Humiliation Factor, namely the sense of humiliation, vulnerability and powerlessness that goes with having one’s integrity violated’ (p. 139). This argument reveals both the strengths and limits of Bufacchi’s approach. His goal is to create a philosophically clear concept of violence. Yet in his attempt to provide a delimited and perspicuous account of violence, Bufacchi ends up bracketing some of the problems that are associated with using this concept in the real world. His ‘third person’, ‘impartial spectator’ conception of violence forces the question about who decides when a person’s integrity has been violated to another level, but it does not eliminate the question. And in Book Reviews 514 r 2010 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Vol. 9, 4, 508–516 making the question of humiliation the key, Bufacchi, though he recognizes ‘social and political dimensions’ to this question, evades the serious problem that we might call, after Peter Bachrach’s famous ‘second face of power’, the ‘second face of violence’ problem. After all, imagine that Shklar is right and some people do not see the injustice, or by extension, the violence committed against them, as humiliating. We might agree that a woman who thinks it is ‘natural’ that her husband will slap her if she makes a comment about the number of beers he has drunk has had her integrity violated, but if she does not, and if she is not humiliated, is it violent? On the one hand, Bufacchi’s impartial spectator is meant to solve this problem. But as many feminist analyses of domestic violence show (Bufacchi makes a passing reference to domestic and family violence at page 24), the ‘objective’ analysis is inadequate to providing any basis for changing the violent situation. Has her integrity been violated if she says, ‘well, I deserved it today and it is no big deal’? Similarly, Fanon’s account of violence does not rest upon ‘identity’, but on something close to what Bufacchi calls ‘humiliation’. Reading Fanon’s accounts of the individual Algerians who have suffered psychological devastation in Wretched of the Earth (Fanon, 1963) might well lead some ‘impartial spectator’ to think that colonialism is intrinsically violent. But suppose the impartial spectator sees such cases as isolated cases of individual devastation, and accepts the idea that colonialism has a civilizing mission (Narayan, 1995). Might not accounts that are ‘subjective’ in such cases prove more revealing about the nature of violence, and what the injustice of such violence is? It was to avoid such gaps between ‘objective’ and ‘subjective’ accounts of violence that lead theorists of structural violence, and Iris Young in defining violence as a ‘face of oppression’ to their conclusions. One wishes that Bufacchi had engaged the feminist literature on the nature of violence more directly, and that he had responded to the logic behind concepts such as structural violence rather than simply criticized them for their vagueness. There are many other questions about violence that we would want a political theory of violence to answer. Bufacchi evades the question about whether humans are intrinsically violent, and thinks his account stronger for this evasion. He also does not consider in depth the psychological questions about the effects of violence on perpetrators and victims. And his account of violence does not help us think about whether it is appropriate to provide ‘restorative justice’ as a remedy for violence. But it is unfair to ask Bufacchi to have taken on all of these questions. As he wisely notes at the outset of this book, the question about the relationship of violence and justice can only become more important to political theory in this new century. In providing such a clear and thoughtful addition to this discussion, he has done a major service to contemporary political theory. Book Reviews 515r 2010 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Vol. 9, 4, 508–516 References Fanon, F. (1963) The Wretched of the Earth. New York: Grove Press. Narayan, U. (1995) Colonialism and its others: Considerations on rights and care discourses. Hypatia 10(2): 133–140. Joan C. Tronto Department of Political Science, University of Minnesota, Minneapolis, USA Book Reviews 516 r 2010 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Vol. 9, 4, 508–516 Violence and social justice References work_fbhnwgm3vjhwdfvqxhx57npr3i ---- 272-5651ndd.indd 300 Nature Vol. 272 23 March 1978 Mr Justice Parker and technical fact Mr Justice Parker, who some time ago handled the Flixborough inquiry into a devastating explosion in a British chemical plant with consummate judicial skill, applied the same talents last year to the proposed construction of THORP (see p298). He was appointed to the Windscale Inquiry, as it became known, perhaps because he had gained experience at Flixborough in inquiries requiring assessment of technical argument. Therefore, as one might expect, where the arguments concerning the con- struction of THORP are capable of strict technical analysis Justice Parker's final report- published by the government on 6 March this year - is masterly. At the lowest level of contention, his description of the basic physics and chemistry of the nuclear fuel cycle should be read by anyone wishing to understand the technical basis of nuclear power and the reprocessing of nuclear fuel. At the next level, Justice Parker 's chapters on risk perform a very valuable function in drawing together the data on the effects of routine discharges of radionuclides from Windscale, and on assessing the possibilities of accident. The Inspector even ordered a few experiments. With their agreement he subjected a few regular ftsh eaters on the coast (where the existing Magnox reprocessing facility discharges low-level liquid waste) to whole body monitoring for the presence of radio- active elements passed down the food chain to the fish and thence to the fish eater. Levels were well below the limits set by the International Commission on Radiological Protection . In such ways Mr Justice Parker allayed some fears about the dangers of Windscale by ascertaining facts . Parker has also made some positive recommendations for improvement, as in the scientific competence of the Nuclear Installations Inspectorate (Nil) to check the designs of THORP were it to be built, and in the constitution of the Windscale local liaison committee. The latter was set up to prepare emergency plans between the local community and Windscale , but, writes the Inspector 'it emerged in evidence that some of those who, in the event of an emergency, would be required to take action under the plan ... did not even know they had any responsibilities, much less know what these responsibilities were. This was clearly a grave defect .. .' British Nuclear Fuels Ltd (BNFL) who control Windscale have agreed to act on all Parker's criticisms so local liaison at least should improve shortly. Politics is involved in the environmental and health risks associated with THORP at least to the extent that being subject to them is not a matter of choice for the local residents; but it seems clear that the risks are not likely to be greater than those involved with any other industry. But in almost all the other issues faced by the Inspector complex political judgements are involved. The two central political questions concerned with the construction of THORP are international and national: the effect on the proliferation of nuclear weapons (which we deal with on p302), and the choice of UK energy future. The latter choice offers a number of options quite distinct from the familiar ones of the high growth and low growth future. On one of these Mr Justice Parker heard two days of evidence (outlined below) from Gerald Leach of Mr Ju stice Parker : " We will be castiga ted anyway" the International Institute for Environ- ment and Deve-lopment (liED) , but he pays scant a ttention -to this in his report. The choice of energy future (in Leach 's paper it is one of low primary energy reached largely by choice of efficient consumption technology) drastically affects Mr Justice Parker's recommendation to build THORP. He argues in his conclusions that : ftr st, extra facilities are ne.eded for pro- jected lJ K arisings of spent fuel after about !995 ; second, the best way of dealing with the wastes is to reprocess the fuel; third, that it is better to build the plant early rather than late to gain experience of the technology and avoid possible technical hitches ; and fourth, ·that if we arc going to have reprocess- ing anyway we might as well improve its economics by importing foreign fuel for treatment . (He disposes of the problem of the prolifera,tion of nuclear weapons on the way by a s.pcc.ial read- ing of the non-proliferation treaty.) Thus the argument depend s on the projected UK arisings, which have their origins in a forecast of the Central Electricity Generating Board. This in turn depends on an energy con sumption forecast. A forecast used in this way represents a political decision. It selects a particular path among many options. Parker's words in the report are illuminating. Considering UK ansmgs of spent fuel to the year 2000 he first calculates that 4,150 tonnes will have a risen from existing reactors and from those under construction. He goes on " If, as appears likely, reactors to pro- duoc a further 4,000 MW per year of electricity are ordered in the ncar future and begin to operate between 1990 and 1995 they will, by the year 2000, have produced a further 1,700 tonnes of spent fuel. Thus a total of 6,000 tonnes by the year 2000 from UK reactors alone is a realistic forecast" . (Another 4,000 MW is a large increase in nuclear power : the total nuclear generating capacity in England and Wales at the end of March last year was 3,462 MW) . It quite genuinely seems not to have occurred to Mr Parker, that the usc of "as appears likely" and "realistic" is, intentionally or nr)t, loaded, repre- senting a choioc of paths among alternatives. For example, the Depart- ment of Energy's recent decision to invest in the conservation of energy is projected by the department to reduce energy consumption by the end of the centry by 20%-or the equivalent of about 40,000 MW . Flexibilities of that order by political choice are quite fea sihle. Energy futures Gerald Leach 's two days of evidence , which formed an interim report on a study to be published by IIED in June, described a future with "substantial rises in ma terial standards, mobility and other energy-related activities". But it required not a rise but a reduction primary energy demand by the year 2000. This is achieved through increased consumption efficiencies with, for example, gas-fired heat pumps for heat- in g and good thermal insulation. The energy group of the Sussex University Science Policy Research Unit has also discovered that market competition between North Sea gas and electricity at the end of the century might restrict electricity to "essential" uses --such as lights, television, and electric motors. It follows, because of the poor energy efficiency of electricity generation in power stations, that on this basis there is a reduction of some 40% in primary energy consumption . Futures studies have lately taken on a completely new meaning , of which Mr Justice Parker does not appear to be aware: the meaning of offering an option to a policy maker, not of pre- dicting the future . Mr Wedgwood Bcnn, the UK Secretary of State for Energy. expressed a view on this at a meeting on Windscalc at the Royal Institution last year: "To be mcs- • Macmillan Journals Ltd 1978 © Nature Publishing Group1978 Nature Vol . 272 23 March 1978 merised by forecasts is a way of getting you to do what the forecaster wants you to do" said Benn. "I want to have elbow room" . Elbow room-in the form of a set of decision options and their probable consequences-is what energy forecasts are now offering; it is false thinking to take only one as "realistic". Mr Justice Parker uses his single set of projected arisings to indicate that the existing Windscale reprocessing facilities, and those already granted planning permission, are insufficient to cope with the load. Waste management The next step is to show that the only effective means of dealing with this excess of spent fuel is to reprocess it- that is, to treat it chemically to separate out the highly act.ive wastes and, as a by.product of the existing process, produce separated uranium and plutonium. (The latter is not an essential step in that it can be reversed to produce a degraded mixture of the two , but it is essential if it is wished to conserve plutonium for bombs or fast breeder reactors). Here again a political element creeps in. The inquiry considered two principal options. The first is as pro- posed for THORP, to reprocess spent fuel rods, separate out the highly active wastes containing fission products and actinides, gla ssify the resul.t and dis- pose of it underground in geologically stabl.e rock formations. The second is to hold the spent fuel in its can, perhaps further encapsulate it , and store it m cooling pond s or in dry vaults (possibly filled with inert gas). Each means of waste management suffers an unresolved technical prob- lem . In the reprocessing route, we do not know if geological storage will work for the I 00,000 years or so for which the actinides are decaying . If it failed, a large amount of radioactivity could be released upon future generations. Equally in the storage route we do not know if the cans (stainless steel in the case of AGR reactors and zirconium alloy in the case of PWRs) will corrode. Agreed scientific knowledge is lack- ing in both cases; and projecting the futures of mate-rials must always be contentious as t·he only conclusive way to test a theory is to wai·t and se.e. Effective work on both has only recently been undertaken . What re- search there has been has concentrated on the re.proce.ss.ing route, as reprocess- ·ing has always been the obje·ctive of the nuclear industry for a rooson other than waste management: 0). This casts some doubt on the validity of the CTA for firm creation. On the one hand, it might be that the estimated negative coefficients associated with the reform after 2008 underestimate the impact: treated cities benefited from a higher trend in firm creation that was so strongly affected that it turned negative after the reform. On the other hand, it is possible that the effect is overestimated: the boom in firm creation between 2006 and 23We exclude the duration of cases at the court level since this is missing in 2008. The results including this variable are qualitatively equivalent and are presented as a robustness check. 24We change the composition of the control group by including the non-treatable cities as a robustness check: see below. 13 2007 would have potentially been offset by a negative trend after 2007, even in the absence of reform. Second, we estimate our econometric model separately for cities that experienced rises and falls in distance to the labor court . The results appear in Tables 3 and 4 respectively, and are depicted in Figures 3 and 4. A number of comments can be made in the light of this new set of estimates. For cities with a rise in distance to the labor court, we have similar but stronger effects compared to the average effect over the entire set of treated cities: job creation, job destruction and new firm creation all fall significantly compared to cities that were unaffected by the reform. Job destruction between 2007 and 2012 was about 4 percentage points (pp) lower in cities with an increased distance to the labor court; the analogous figures for job creation and the creation of new firms are 4.6 pp and 6.3 pp respectively. In other words, labor-market functioning there was significantly degraded by the reform. Employers were less likely to hire new employees, fire existing employees and create new firms. The overall effect on unemployment is not statistically significant, but the coefficient is positive. For cities with a fall in the distance to the labor court, the results are opposite but insignificant (i.e. higher job destruction and creation). The lack of significance might reflect two technical considerations, as Figure 2 shows. First, only relatively few cities experienced a fall in distance (108) compared to the number with a rise (1,093), which reduces statistical power. Second, the average fall in distance is relatively small (-11.3 km) compared to the average increase in distance (+25.7 km). The smaller sample size and weaker treatment are likely behind the lack of significance for cities with a fall in distance. Robustness We explore the sensitivity of our findings to changes in the control group and esti- mation method. We first re-estimate the above specifications including the untreatable cities in the control group. The results in Tables A1 to A3 in the Online Appendix are similar. Second, we reconsider the above specifications for the two types of treated cities using a multilevel mixed effects model. We introduce random effects at the city and court × year level (φc(i),t). The vector of covariates Xit is decomposed into covariates that are defined at the city level (X1,it) and those that are defined at the court level (X2,c(i)t) The multilevel model is: yit = βX1,it + µt + αi + φc(i),t + ∑ s 6=2007 φs(Di ×1s=t) + uit (2) αi = γ0 + ei φc(i),t = λX2,c(i)t + �c(i),t where λ includes an intercept, uit is a random term at the city × year level, ei a random term at the city level, and �c(i),t a random term at the court × year level. The estimates from this model for the two separate samples (e.g. rising or falling distance) appear in Tables A4 and A5 in the Online Appendix and are similar to those shown previously, i.e. a significant fall in job destruction, job creation and new firms in cities that had a rise in distance to the labor court, and insignificant rises in job destruction and creation for cities with a smaller distance. 14 CTA Two variables may be suspected of violating the Common Trend Assumption in the above regressions. First, the number of new firms seems to have grown faster between 2006 and 2007 in treated compared to control cities (Table 2). This effect is mainly due to cities whose distance to the labor court increased (Table 3). Second, unemployment rose significantly more in cities where the distance to the labor court fell compared to the control group (Table 4). We now turn to matching methods to correct the control group sample and ensure the validity of the Common Trend Assumption. Figure 3: The marginal effects of the reform in cities that experienced a rise in the distance to the labor court. (Differences-in-differences) − 6 − 4 − 2 0 2 2006 2008 2010 2012 Year Job Destructions − 1 0 − 5 0 5 2006 2008 2010 2012 Year Job Creations − 2 0 2 4 6 2006 2008 2010 2012 Year Unemployed Workers − 1 0 − 5 0 5 1 0 2006 2008 2010 2012 Year New Enterprises Note: The confidence intervals are at the 95% confidence level. The outcomes are normalized to 100 in 2007. These are regression-adjusted differences-in-differences, with standard errors clustered at the court level. 5.2 Conditional Differences-in-Differences The results above reveal the potential violation of CTA is for some of our outcomes. We therefore propose to correct our estimations by weighting the sample control to produce a sample of untreated cities with a pre-reform trend similar to that in treated cities. We first estimate a propensity score and then run the above regressions with the weights derived from a matching algorithm. 5.2.1 Matching To obtain similar pre-reform trends, we estimate the propensity score at the city level, i.e. the probability that a city have its associated court removed, based on the change between 2006 and 15 Figure 4: The marginal effects of the reform in cities that experienced a fall in the distance to the labor court. (Differences-in-differences) − 1 0 − 5 0 5 1 0 2006 2008 2010 2012 Year Job Destructions − 5 0 5 1 0 2006 2008 2010 2012 Year Job Creations − 1 0 − 5 0 5 1 0 2006 2008 2010 2012 Year Unemployed Workers − 2 0 − 1 0 0 1 0 2 0 2006 2008 2010 2012 Year New Enterprises Note: The confidence intervals are at the 95% confidence level. The outcomes are normalized to 100 in 2007. These are regression-adjusted differences-in-differences, with standard errors clustered at the court level. 2007 of the variables of interest (job creation, job destruction, unemployment and new firms).25 This matching on pre-reform trends aims to correct for any pre-trend differences in the DiD estimation. The removal decision is defined as: removal∗i = γ∆Yi + ui (3) where removal∗ is the latent variable associated with removal (which is set to 1 if the labor court associated with city i was removed and 0 if not). ∆Yi are the changes in labor-market outcomes between 2006 and 2007. We consider a number of matching algorithms to calculate weights based on the propensity score from the above equation. We consider in turn the Epanechnikov Kernel (EK), Gaussian Ker- nel (GK), and three-nearest neighbor algorithm (N3). We further use a fourth matching algorithm, the Covariate Balancing Propensity Score (CBPS) method. This technique relies on GMM estima- tion, and jointly estimates the propensity score and the associated weights so as to minimize the 25Matching is effected on the changes between 2006 and 2007 rather than between 2007 and 2008 to avoid potential anticipation effects, as the reform was discussed, voted and ratified in 2008. 16 ex-post bias between the treated and control groups. Comparing Matching Techniques Table 5 presents the average standardized bias (ASB) in each matching model. It also shows, for each estimation, the number of variables with standardized bias above 5%.26 We present two sets of results: on the left-hand side we show the ASB for the matching procedure in cities whose distance to the labor court rose; the right-hand side shows the analogous results for cities whose distance fell. First of all, the data reveal relatively little heterogeneity in the pre-reform trends: the ASB figure is below the 5% threshold for cities with increased distance and below the 10% threshold for cities with lower distance. We note however that half of the labor-market outcomes can be considered as biased, i.e. as having statistically different trends between 2006 and 2007. This justifies the use of matching to produce a control group with pre-reform trends similar to those in treated cities. Second, regarding the matching algorithm, the CBPS seems to be the most efficient way of reducing the ASB, with the values of the latter falling from 4.44 (resp. 7.25) in the unmatched sample to 0.06 (resp. 0.03) in the matched sample for cities with greater (lower) distance. The CBPS algorithm also minimizes the number of biased variables. The Nearest Neighbor Algorithm (N3) is the second-best matching algorithm in terms of the ASB. 5.2.2 The Results of Conditional Differences-in-differences We now estimate equation 1 with the weights from the CBPS matching algorithm.27 Given that the reform seems to have had different effects according to the change in distance (higher or lower), we estimate an ATT separately by type of affected city. Table 6 and Figure 5 display the results of this new estimation for cities with greater distance to the labor court. We first note a substantial improvement in the CTA, which now holds for all outcomes. Second, this new set of results confirms the original findings: cities with greater distance to the labor court suffered from lower job destruction (about -3.8 percentage points between 2007 and 2012), job creation (-5.8 pp) and new-firm creation (-5.4 pp). The results for cities with a fall in distance (Table 7 and Figure 6) reveal no significant effects of the reform. However, as in the DiD framework, the results by city type are mirror images of each other, with increased job creation and destruction in this second set of cities. Here again, insignificance likely reflects the less-pronounced treatment in these cities, and the relatively small number of cities with lower distance. Robustness We explore additional specifications to test the robustness of the above results. We first include non-treatable cities in the control group, i.e. cities whose labor court could not have been removed by the reform (Online Appendix, Tables A7 and A8). Second, we add the average duration of terminated cases in the associated labor court to the control variables (Online Appendix, Tables A9 and A10). For this latter, we exclude observations in 2008 for which the Ministry of 26The 5% threshold is usually used in the literature following the original paper of Heckman et al. (1998). 27We use the Stata xtreg package to estimate the model with weights, clustering observations at the pre-reform labor court level. 17 Justice data has many missing values.28 Third, we estimate the above models using the second-best matching algorithm in terms of bias reduction (N3: Online Appendix, Tables A11 and A12) Finally, we use the CBPS scores with the multilevel mixed-effects model with the same specification as in the previous section (Online Appendix, Tables A13 and A14). All of these alternative estimations yield the same results as in the main text above: the reform had no significant effect on cities with lower distance to the labor court, but a negative effect on job creation, job destruction and new-firm creation for cities where this distance rose. Figure 5: Marginal effects of the reform for cities that experienced a rise in the distance to the labor court. (Conditional Differences-in-differences) − 6 − 4 − 2 0 2 4 2006 2008 2010 2012 Year Job Destructions − 1 0 − 5 0 5 2006 2008 2010 2012 Year Job Creations − 2 0 2 4 6 2006 2008 2010 2012 Year Unemployed Workers − 1 0 − 5 0 5 1 0 2006 2008 2010 2012 Year New Enterprises Note: The confidence intervals are at the 95% confidence level. The outcomes are normalized to 100 in 2007. These are regression-adjusted differences-in-differences, with standard errors clustered at the court level. 5.3 Linear Impact of the Distance The above sections have presented the overall impact of the reform for two groups of cities: those that experienced an increased in distance to their labor courts, and those that experienced a fall. We now propose to estimate a linear specification, which seeks to estimate the impact of one additional kilometer to the associated labor court. We assume here that distance has a linear impact on the labor market outcomes, and that an increase and a fall of distance have similar but opposite effects. The associated specification is: 28We prefer to drop data in 2008 rather than only the missing values, as the estimations are carried out using weights, which are calculated using the entire sample. Dropping one year for every observation does not affect the validity of the matching process. 18 Figure 6: Marginal effects of the reform for cities that experienced a fall in the distance to the labor court. (Conditional Differences-in-differences) − 5 0 5 1 0 2006 2008 2010 2012 Year Job Destructions − 5 0 5 1 0 2006 2008 2010 2012 Year Job Creations − 2 0 2 4 6 8 2006 2008 2010 2012 Year Unemployed Workers − 2 0 − 1 0 0 1 0 2 0 2006 2008 2010 2012 Year New Enterprises Note: The confidence intervals are at the 95% confidence level. The outcomes are normalized to 100 in 2007. These are regression-adjusted differences-in-differences, with standard errors clustered at the court level. yit = βXit + µt + αi + ∑ s 6=2007 φs1s=t∆i + uit (4) where ∆i represents the change of distance to the associated labor court. It is equal to zero for non-treated cities for all periods, and to the change of the distance for treated cities due to the reform. This specification allows us to estimate the impact of one additional kilometer for each year after the reform. Results of this estimation are displayed in tables 8 (without matching correction) and 9 (with matching correction). First of all, one can observe that the coefficient associated to the reform change of distance is significant for New Enterprises in 2006 in absence of matching correction (table 8). This suggests that, prior to the reform, cities in the sample differ in the number of New Entreprises according to the future change in distance. The matching correction successfully erases these differences, and no effect is significant in 2006 once we use a weighted specification (table 9). Results with the matching correction are graphically displayed on figure 7. As one can see, an increase of distance to the labor court significantly decreases job destructions, job creations and, eventually, the firm creations in the subsequent years. For an increase of 10 kilometers, we 19 estimate that the growth rate between 2006 and 2012 was lower by 0.8 percentage points for job destructions, by 1.5 percentage points for job creations, and by 1.8 percentage points for new firms. Results including non-treatable cities, displayed in the Online Appendix (tables A15 and A16), lead to similar observations. Figure 7: Marginal effects of an increase of one kilometer in the distance to the labor court on affected cities. (Linear specification, with matching-correction) − .1 5 − .1 − .0 5 0 .0 5 .1 2006 2008 2010 2012 Year Job Destruction − .3 − .2 − .1 0 .1 2006 2008 2010 2012 Year Job Creation − .1 − .0 5 0 .0 5 .1 .1 5 2006 2008 2010 2012 Year Unemployment − .3 − .2 − .1 0 .1 .2 2006 2008 2010 2012 Year New Firms Note: The confidence intervals are at the 95% confidence level. The outcomes are normalized to 100 in 2007. Standard errors clustered at the court level. 5.4 Limitations Our empirical investigation attempted to address most of the challenges public-policy evaluations generally face. However, two main issues were not tackled here, as the necessary econometric tools have not yet been developed. First, we are aware that the estimation of the propensity score might produce measurement errors, which are not taken into account here. Abadie and Imbens (2016) show that propensity-score estimation affects the large-sample distribution of the matching estimator. Their contribution is however to date limited to the ATT without regression adjustment. Further developments (especially in regression adjustment and conditional DiD) are required to correct for the potential biases in our case. Second, the matching algorithm might generate a need for additional clustering between matched units. Abadie and Spiess (2016) derive results for the K-nearest neighbors matching technique without replacement. This is the simplest matching algorithm, as the clusters are exclusive, and we have no doubt that these results will be extended 20 to more complex matching algorithms in the coming years. 6 Conclusion and Discussion Public decision-makers usually face a trade-off between two (opposite) policy goals: limiting public expenditure and ensuring the good functioning of the labor market. In recent years, this dual optimization problem has received increasing attention, with rising concern about national debt and the sharp increase in unemployment in developed countries. In June 2016, the IMF stated: "[The risks of stagnation] are particularly worrisome for the euro area, given the high level of unemployment and public and private debt in some member countries".29 Public authorities have thus devoted particular attention to reductions in public expenditure that would have the smallest effect on the economy and, in particular, the labor market. One popular proposal among public decision-makers has been to rationalize public administra- tion in order to reduce its costs. A number of countries have thus sought to reduce their number of (labor) courts. However, the impact of such reforms on the labor market has received little attention from public authorities given the lack of associated empirical evidence. Our paper is the first piece of empirical analysis to assess the impact of labor-court access on the labor market. We do so by exploiting the 2008 French reform that removed one quarter of the labor courts in France. We distinguish between two types of cities that were affected by the reform: those with increased and reduced distance to the labor court. The estimation of (conditional) differences-in-differences reveals that greater distance is associated with worse-performing labor markets: lower job destruction (-4 percentage points), job creation (-4.6 pp) and new-firm creation (-6.3 pp) between 2006 and 2012 for cities with a greater distance compared to unaffected cities. We also find opposite-signed but insignificant effects in cities where the distance to the labor court fell (i.e. higher job destruction and creation). These results cast some doubt on the net benefit of such reforms. There are multiple effects on both public spending and economic activity. Labor courts are a key institution for the enforcement of labor contracts, and access to them affects economic behavior. Our results suggest that greater distance brings about higher costs. Our interpretation is that these latter can be particularly heavy for small-sized firms, which represent the majority of firms in France, as described in Section 3.1. Employers in these firms are particularly affected by the changes in litigation costs resulting from court accessibility. The regions that were affected by the reform already had weaker labor markets prior to the reform. Their economic network was mainly composed of smaller firms: these employers are particularly affected by the changes in litigation costs due to court access. The costs can be both direct (transportation costs) and indirect (opportunity cost of going to court). As the presence of both parties is mandatory at certain stages of the procedure (even though the party can be represented for others) the repeated costs of greater distance might translate into a substantial burden for employers. Overall, our estimations show that the increased burden for both employees and employers leads to worse labor-market performance. 29https://www.imf.org/external/pubs/ft/fandd/2016/06/pdf/lin.pdf. https://www.imf.org/external/pubs/ft/fandd/2016/06/pdf/lin.pdf 21 Acknowledgements We are grateful to Pierre Cahuc, Laurent Davezies, Xavier d’Haultfoeuille and Francis Kramarz for discussions which led to improvements in the paper. We also thank participants at the CREST seminar, the Law & Economics Workshop (Florence, 2016), the LAGV conference (Aix-en-Provence, 2016), the EEA conference (Geneva, 2016), the AFSE conference (Nancy, 2016) and the TEPP winter school (Aussois, 2016). 22 References Abadie, A. and Imbens, G. W. (2016). Matching on the Estimated Propensity Score. Econometrica, 84(2):781–807. Abadie, A. and Spiess, J. (2016). Robust Post-Matching Inference. Working Paper. Acemoglu, D. and Johnson, S. (2005). Unbundling Institutions. Journal of Political Economy, 113(5):949–995. Bauer, T. K., Bender, S., and Bonin, H. (2007). Dismissal Protection and Worker Flows in Small Establishments. Economica, 74(296):804–821. Behaghel, L., Crépon, B., and Sédillot, B. (2008). The perverse effects of partial employment protection reform: The case of French older workers. Journal of Public Economics, 92(3-4):696– 721. Chappe, N. and Obidzinski, M. (2014). The Impact of the Number of Courts on the Demand for Trials. International Review of Law and Economics, 37:121–125. Chemin, M. (2009). The impact of the judiciary on entrepreneurship: Evaluation of Pakistan’s Access to Justice Programme. Journal of Public Economics, 93(1-2):114–125. Chemin, M. (2012). Does Court Speed Shape Economic Activity? Evidence from a Court Reform in India. Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 28(3):460–485. Cour des comptes (2015). Rapport public annuel 2015. Technical report. Djankov, S., La Porta, R., López-de Silanes, F., and Shleifer, A. (2003). Courts. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 118(2):453–517. ENCJ (2012). Judicial Reform in Europe, 2011-2012. Technical report. Espinosa, R., Desrieux, C., and Wan, H. (2017). Fewer Courts, less Justice? Evidence from the 2008 French Reform of Labour Courts. European Journal of Law and Economics, forthcoming. Fraisse, H., Kramarz, F., and Prost, C. (2014). Labor disputes and labor flows. Industrial and Labor Relations Review, forthcoming. Garibaldi, P., Borgarello, A., and Pacelli, L. (2003). Employment protection legislation and the size of firms: A close look at the Italian case . Giornale degli Economisti e Annali di Economia, 63(1):33–68. Gianfreda, G. and Vallanti, G. (2015). Labour Courts delays and the composition of employment: Is labour encouraged or endangered by institutions? Working papers luisslab, Dipartimento di Economia e Finanza, LUISS Guido Carli. Gomes, C. (2007). The Transformation of the Portuguese Judicial Organization: between Efficiency and Democracy. Utrecht Law Review, 3(1):101–111. Guilloneau, M. and Serverin, E. (2015). Les litiges individuels du travail de 2004 à 2013: des actions moins nombreuses mais toujours plus contentieuses. Technical Report 135, Infostat, Ministère de la Justice. 23 Heckman, J. J., Ichimura, H., and Todd, P. (1998). Matching As An Econometric Evaluation Estimator. Review of Economic Studies, 65:261–294. Hernanz, V., Jimeno, J., and Kugler, A. (2005). Employment consequences of restrictive permanent contracts: Evidence from Spanish labour market reforms. CEPR Discussion Paper No. 3724. Kugler, A. and Pica, G. (2008). Effects of employment protection on worker and job flows: Evidence from the 1990 Italian reform. Labour Economics, 15(1):78–95. Kugler, A. D. and Saint-Paul, G. (2004). How Do Firing Costs Affect Worker Flows in a World with Adverse Selection? Journal of Labor Economics, 22(3):553–584. Le Barbanchon, T. and Malherbet, F. (2013). An anatomy of the French labor market. Technical Report Employment Working paper 142, International Labour Office. Mak, E. (2008). Balancing Territoriality and Functionality; Specialization as a Tool for Reforming Jurisdiction in the Netherlands, France and Germany. International Journal for Court Adminis- tration, 1(2):2–9. Marcus, J. (2014). Does Job Loss Make You Smoke and Gain Weight? Economica, 81(324):626–648. Ministère de la Justice (2011). La réforme de la carte Judiciaire. Technical report, L’Actu Justice. Morgan, S. L. and Harding, D. J. (2006). Matching estimators of causal effects: Prospects and pitfalls in theory and practice. Sociological Methods & Research, 35(1):3–60. Rosenbaum, P. and Rubin, D. (1983). The Central Role of the Propensity Score in Observational Studies for Causal Effects. Biometrika, 70:41–55. Schivardi, F. and Torrini, R. (2008). Identifying the effects of firing restrictions through size- contingent differences in regulation. Labour Economics, 15(3):482–511. Sénat (2012). La réforme de la carte judiciaire: une occasion manquée. Technical report, Rap- port d’Information de Mme Nicole Borvo Cohen-Seat et M. Yves Détraigne, fait au nom de la commission des lois. Tresor-Eco (2014). Le traitement des litiges en droit du travail : constats et perspectives economiques. Technical Report 137, Lettre du Minsitere de l’Economie, de l’Industrie et du Numerique. Van Djik, F. and Horatius, D. (2013). Judiciary in Times of Scarcity: Retrenchment and Reform. International Journal for Court Administration, 5(1):15–24. Visaria, S. (2009). Legal Reform and Loan Repayment: The Microeconomic Impact of Debt Recov- ery Tribunals in India. American Economic Journal: Applied Economics, 1(3):59–81. von Below, D. and Thoursie, P. S. (2010). Last in, first out?: Estimating the effect of seniority rules in Sweden. Labour Economics, 17(6):987–997. Von Lilienfeld-Toal, U., Mookherjee, D., and Visaria, S. (2012). The Distributive Impact of Re- forms in Credit Enforcement: Evidence From Indian Debt Recovery Tribunals. Econometrica, 80(2):497–558. World Bank (2011). Improving the Performance of Justice Institutions. Technical report. 24 Appendix 1: Maps of Judicial System Figure 8: French courts before the reform and removals during the reform 25 Figure 9: French courts after the reform 26 Appendix 2: Tables Table 1: Summary statistics in 2007. Variable Label Non-treatable Removed Receiving Untreated unemployed Number of unemployed workers 290.044 157.265*** 262.401 252.625 (966.2) (304.6) (1054.34) (863.3) jobDest Number of job destructions (registration for unemployment benefits) 383.916 213.514*** 372.36 348.375 (1250.4) (412.6) (1626.2) (1278.6) jobCrea Number of unemployed workers who left unemployment benefits after finding a job 107.877 75.392*** 115.219 107.769 (293.1) (122.7) (415.8) (304.2) newEntr Number of firms created per year 24.321 12.739*** 23.581 23.775 (75.49) ( 22.70) (103.80) (81.34) distance Distance between the city and its labor court (km) 28.986 17.178*** 22.005*** 28.618 (23.082) (13.215) (21.791) (54.593) pop Population (log) 7.728 7.614*** 7.768 7.803 (.95) (.783) (.926) (.95) popAge Working age population (log) 7.253 7.159*** 7.326 7.355 (.962) (.779) (.931) (.955) propCS1 Proportion of individuals in the 1st social category .02 .015 .012*** .014 (.023) (.019) (.017) (.019) propCS2 Proportion of individuals in the 2nd social category .039 .036*** .037*** .038 (.016) (.017) (.016) (.017) propCS3 Proportion of individuals in the 3rd social category .05 .054*** .072*** .068 (.027) (.03) (.043) (.047) propCS4 Proportion of individuals in the 4th social category .124 .13*** .145*** .14 (.041) (.04) (.044) (.043) propCS5 Proportion of individuals in the 5th social category .169 .162*** .168** .166 (.033) (.035) (.035) (.036) propCS6 Proportion of individuals in the 6th social category .158 .179*** .152*** .158 (.051) (.054) (.052) (.056) propCS7 Proportion of individuals in the 7th social category .298 .274*** .262** .266 (.081) (.062) (.069) (.074) propCS8 Proportion of individuals in the 8th social category .142 .15 .153** .15 (.042) (.042) (.042) (.041) newAff� Number of new claims per year 991.7 196.2*** 1266*** 926.556 (1108.0) (72.3) (1268) (987.413) succRate� Success rate for plaintiffs .712 .74*** .722*** .714 (.092) (.128) (.081) (.074) concRate� Conciliation rate .107 .127*** .118*** .108 (.052) (.054) (.047) (.051) depRate� Rate of départage 16.59 8.28*** 13.94 14.067 (9.624) (10.353) (8.769) (10.205) durAff� Average duration of terminated cases in months (log) 10.443 8.355*** 11.099** 10.94 (2.676) (2.378) (3.059) (3.058) Means and standard deviations (in parentheses). Variables with � are reported at the labor-court level. Stars indicate that the sample mean is statistically different from the untreated cities’ sample mean at the 10% (*), 5% (**) and 1% (***) levels. 28 Table 2: Estimation of the difference between cities not affected by the reform and cities whose labor court was removed (Differences-in-differences, regression-adjusted, excluding non-treatable cities). Job Destruction Job Creation Unemployment New Firms φ2006 -0.554 0.705 -0.0908 -5.252** (1.031) (1.345) (0.533) (2.445) φ2008 -0.766 -1.250 0.0920 1.433 (0.782) (1.152) (0.435) (2.684) φ2009 -0.444 -3.456** 0.126 -3.481 (1.462) (1.504) (0.829) (2.403) φ2010 -2.076 -4.020** 0.140 -3.357 (1.443) (1.862) (1.223) (2.268) φ2011 -2.661* -2.730 1.556 -5.236** (1.425) (2.061) (1.561) (2.049) φ2012 -3.536*** -3.879** 1.364 -5.771*** (1.222) (1.919) (1.589) (1.973) City FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Year FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Covariates Yes Yes Yes Yes Observations 50,376 50,376 50,372 49,497 R-squared 0.255 0.151 0.341 0.279 Significance level: *** significant at the 1% level; ** significant at the 5% level; * significant at the 10% level. Robust standard errors are clustered at the court level. 29 Table 3: Estimation of the difference between cities not affected by the reform and cities that experienced a rise in the distance to the labor court (Differences-in-differences, regression-adjusted, excluding non-treatable cities). Job Destruction Job Creation Unemployment New Firms φI,2006 -0.579 0.596 0.108 -5.547** (1.105) (1.356) (0.565) (2.624) φI,2008 -0.789 -1.723 -0.00714 1.181 (0.729) (1.163) (0.458) (2.855) φI,2009 -0.411 -4.187*** 0.0137 -3.976 (1.487) (1.538) (0.897) (2.429) φI,2010 -2.506* -4.781** 0.107 -4.021* (1.427) (1.957) (1.270) (2.298) φI,2011 -3.118** -3.319 1.576 -4.979** (1.349) (2.109) (1.625) (2.188) φI,2012 -3.952*** -4.651** 1.475 -6.323*** (1.200) (1.993) (1.646) (2.051) City FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Year FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Covariates Yes Yes Yes Yes Observations 49,640 49,640 49,636 48,768 R-squared 0.255 0.152 0.340 0.279 Significance level: *** significant at the 1% level; ** significant at the 5% level; * significant at the 10% level. Robust standard errors are clustered at the court level. 30 Table 4: Estimation of the difference between cities not affected by the reform and cities that experienced a fall in the distance to the labor court (Differences-in-differences, regression-adjusted, excluding non-treatable cities). Job Destruction Job Creation Unemployment New Firms φD,2006 -0.271 1.603 -2.057** -2.375 (1.340) (2.488) (0.923) (6.703) φD,2008 -0.324 3.504 1.351 3.859 (2.451) (2.222) (1.107) (4.897) φD,2009 -1.282 4.058* 0.306 1.490 (2.542) (2.199) (1.637) (4.476) φD,2010 2.015 3.773 -0.343 3.033 (3.320) (3.825) (2.273) (5.659) φD,2011 1.746 3.238 0.592 -8.051* (4.530) (2.973) (3.116) (4.697) φD,2012 0.591 3.922 -0.463 -0.630 (3.303) (2.829) (3.000) (3.727) City FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Year FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Covariates Yes Yes Yes Yes Observations 42,891 42,891 42,901 42,228 R-squared 0.267 0.138 0.348 0.278 Significance level: *** significant at the 1% level; ** significant at the 5% level; * significant at the 10% level. Robust standard errors are clustered at the court level. 31 Table 5: Diagnosis of the matching process: Average standardized bias and number of biased variables at 5% (excluding non-treatable cities). Increased Distance Reduced Distance Algorithm Average Bias №. Biased Var. Average Bias №. Biased Var. Before Matching 4.44 2 7.25 2 EK 2.82 0 7.28 2 GK 3.63 0 7.27 2 N3 1.28 0 4.92 2 CBPS 0.06 0 0.03 0 Table 6: Estimation of the difference between cities not affected by the reform and cities that expe- rienced a rise in the distance to the labor court (Conditional differences-in-differences, regression- adjusted, excluding non-treatable cities). Job Destruction Job Creation Unemployment New Firms φI,2006 -0.0423 -0.206 -0.330 0.354 (1.015) (1.326) (0.526) (2.525) φI,2008 -0.349 -2.461** -0.172 4.300 (0.727) (1.149) (0.440) (2.809) φI,2009 0.145 -5.085*** -0.0715 -3.089 (1.474) (1.626) (1.057) (2.538) φI,2010 -2.102 -5.848*** 0.192 -2.825 (1.392) (2.033) (1.426) (2.327) φI,2011 -2.845** -4.582** 1.765 -4.116* (1.316) (2.120) (1.786) (2.255) φI,2012 -3.834*** -5.792*** 1.299 -5.420** (1.177) (2.058) (1.829) (2.264) City FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Year FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Covariates Yes Yes Yes Yes Observations 48,752 48,752 48,755 48,754 R-squared 0.234 0.190 0.330 0.290 Significance level: *** significant at the 1% level; ** significant at the 5% level; * significant at the 10% level. Robust standard errors are clustered at the court level. 32 Table 7: Estimation of the difference between cities not affected by the reform and cities that ex- perienced a fall in the distance to the labor court (Conditional differences-in-differences, regression- adjusted, excluding non-treatable cities). Job Destruction Job Creation Unemployment New Firms φD,2006 0.641 0.00567 -0.151 -3.459 (1.290) (2.343) (0.900) (6.968) φD,2008 -1.097 2.990 1.296 4.696 (2.305) (2.206) (1.170) (4.812) φD,2009 -0.314 1.644 2.554** 0.0869 (2.293) (2.373) (1.234) (5.558) φD,2010 2.958 1.755 1.978 2.969 (3.072) (3.366) (1.963) (6.231) φD,2011 2.661 1.296 2.881 -8.300 (4.172) (3.150) (2.535) (5.249) φD,2012 0.622 2.636 2.833 0.421 (3.136) (2.715) (2.615) (4.030) City FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Year FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Covariates Yes Yes Yes Yes Observations 42,226 42,226 42,229 42,228 R-squared 0.272 0.130 0.381 0.282 Significance level: *** significant at the 1% level; ** significant at the 5% level; * significant at the 10% level. Robust standard errors are clustered at the court level. 33 Table 8: Linear estimation of the effect of a change of distance. (No matching-correction, excluding non-treatable cities.) Job Destruction Job Creation Unemployment New Firms φ2006 -0.0129 0.0426 0.0183 -0.145** (0.0361) (0.0382) (0.0195) (0.0708) φ2008 -0.0283 -0.0666** -0.00349 -0.0245 (0.0203) (0.0331) (0.0128) (0.0843) φ2009 -0.0131 -0.141*** -0.00997 -0.123* (0.0436) (0.0420) (0.0232) (0.0667) φ2010 -0.0973*** -0.140*** -0.0129 -0.138* (0.0291) (0.0532) (0.0302) (0.0760) φ2011 -0.0976*** -0.103* 0.0292 -0.123** (0.0335) (0.0568) (0.0495) (0.0607) φ2012 -0.0950*** -0.123** 0.0473 -0.219*** (0.0333) (0.0520) (0.0455) (0.0462) City FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Year FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Covariates Yes Yes Yes Yes Observations 50,371 50,371 50,367 49,492 R-squared 0.255 0.151 0.341 0.279 Significance level: *** significant at the 1% level; ** significant at the 5% level; * significant at the 10% level. Robust standard errors are clustered at the court level. 34 Table 9: Linear estimation of the effect of a change of distance. (With matching-correction, exclud- ing non-treatable cities.) Job Destruction Job Creation Unemployment New Firms φ2006 -0.00765 0.00242 0.0151 -0.0287 (0.0323) (0.0330) (0.0185) (0.0663) φ2008 -0.0139 -0.111*** -0.0129 0.00129 (0.0204) (0.0272) (0.00988) (0.0844) φ2009 -0.00485 -0.178*** -0.0206 -0.0939 (0.0444) (0.0358) (0.0233) (0.0654) φ2010 -0.0937*** -0.169*** -0.0202 -0.111 (0.0253) (0.0506) (0.0271) (0.0772) φ2011 -0.0925*** -0.147*** 0.0192 -0.0751 (0.0319) (0.0494) (0.0498) (0.0568) φ2012 -0.0807** -0.151*** 0.0429 -0.188*** (0.0316) (0.0479) (0.0468) (0.0425) City FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Year FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Covariates Yes Yes Yes Yes Observations 49,476 49,476 49,479 49,478 R-squared 0.236 0.185 0.333 0.289 Significance level: *** significant at the 1% level; ** significant at the 5% level; * significant at the 10% level. Robust standard errors are clustered at the court level. 35 Appendix 3: Decision to remove courts The decision to remove courts in 2008 mainly resulted from the government’s will to reduce public expenditures. In French history, reductions of the number of courts, and more broadly amendments of the judicial map, turn to be rare events. Indeed, prior to 2008, the last significant reform dated back to 1958. In 2008, the government had therefore a unique opportunity to substantially amend the judicial map. During the preliminary discussions, the government declared that the courts to be removed would be chosen in the light of their level of activity. We propose here a few elements to see whether (i) the government effectively based its choice on the court’s activity level, and (ii) whether some dimensions of the labor market under scrutiny affected its decision. To do so, we consider data of 2007 at the court level. The dependent variable is a dummy variable equal to 1 if the court was removed and to 0 otherwise. The independent variables include variables about the court (the number of new cases, the average delay to obtain a decision, the average winning rate for the plaintiffs, the average conciliation rate, and the average so-called dé- partage rate which accounts for a procedure specific to French labor courts), and average values of the job market outcomes considered in our study (job destructions, job creations, new enterprises, unemployed workers).30 Table 10 shows the results of probit estimation of the probability of a court to be removed. It excludes labor courts that were unique in their département, since the government refused to remove such courts. Sample A includes removed courts and courts that were not affected by the reform. Sample B also includes courts that took on the competency of removed courts. As one can see, the court’s activity, i.e. the number of new cases, has been the main criterion to determine the removal of courts. We observe indeed that this only criterion explains almost 47% of the removal decision. Furthermore, it appears that the government did not consider issues related to the labor market conditions when deciding on the reform: none of the coefficients associated to these variables is significant in the regression. 30Note that the averages of the outcome variables are weighted by the population in working age. 36 Table 10: Probit regressions of the probability of being removed. (Z-values in parentheses.) (1) (2) (3) (4) Sample A Sample B Sample A Sample B New Cases -0.0097*** -0.0093*** -0091*** -0.0092*** (-5.16) (-5.34) (-5.94) (-6.13) Winning Rate 1.100 1.527 -0.89 -1.33 Conciliation Rate 1.428 1.107 -0.57 -0.47 Départage Rate 0.0058 0.0113 -0.43 -0.86 Job destructions -0.0010 -0.0017 (-0.57) (-1.02) Job creations 0.0011 0.0020 -0.3 -0.55 New Enterprises 0.0031 0.0029 -0.25 -0.26 Unemployed Workers 0.0007 0.0012 -0.55 -1.01 Average Duration -0.1326** -0.1337** (-2.14) (-2.23) Observations 142 189 142 189 Pseudo R2 0.5051 0.4996 0.4669 0.4609 1 Online Appendix Labor Market & Access to Justice Romain Espinosa, Claudine Desrieux and Marc Ferracci Differences-in-Differences Table A1: Estimation of the difference between cities not affected by the reform and cities whose labor court was removed (Differences-in-differences, regression-adjusted, excluding non-treatable cities). Job Destruction Job Creation Unemployment New Firms φ2006 -0.691 0.626 -0.109 -5.707** (1.040) (1.315) (0.529) (2.403) φ2008 -0.610 -1.114 0.149 0.626 (0.782) (1.129) (0.422) (2.682) φ2009 0.107 -3.465** 0.184 -3.210 (1.453) (1.494) (0.829) (2.389) φ2010 -1.786 -3.698** 0.206 -3.054 (1.437) (1.836) (1.216) (2.243) φ2011 -2.485* -2.468 1.677 -4.493** (1.411) (2.035) (1.539) (2.033) φ2012 -3.463*** -3.668* 1.530 -5.394*** (1.210) (1.880) (1.562) (1.972) City FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Year FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Covariates Yes Yes Yes Yes Observations 57,124 57,121 57,120 56,147 R-squared 0.243 0.155 0.340 0.279 Significance level: *** significant at the 1% level; ** significant at the 5% level; * significant at the 10% level. Robust standard errors are clustered at the court level. 2 Table A2: Estimation of the difference between cities not affected by the reform and cities that experienced a rise in the distance to the labor court (Differences-in-differences, regression-adjusted, including non-treatable cities). Job Destruction Job Creation Unemployment New Firms φI,2006 -0.710 0.521 0.0904 -5.991** (0.525) (0.695) (0.872) (0.0216) φI,2008 -0.632 -1.580 0.0515 0.375 (0.387) (0.168) (0.908) (0.895) φI,2009 0.142 -4.201*** 0.0706 -3.706 (0.923) (0.00642) (0.937) (0.127) φI,2010 -2.215 -4.461** 0.172 -3.718 (0.120) (0.0220) (0.892) (0.103) φI,2011 -2.937** -3.056 1.697 -4.227* (0.0281) (0.144) (0.291) (0.0532) φI,2012 -3.874*** -4.442** 1.640 -5.934*** (0.00122) (0.0239) (0.312) (0.00419) City FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Year FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Covariates Yes Yes Yes Yes Observations 56,388 56,385 56,384 55,418 R-squared 0.243 0.157 0.340 0.279 Significance level: *** significant at the 1% level; ** significant at the 5% level; * significant at the 10% level. Robust standard errors are clustered at the court level. 3 Table A3: Estimation of the difference between cities not affected by the reform and cities that experienced a fall in the distance to the labor court (Differences-in-differences, regression-adjusted, including non-treatable cities). Job Destruction Job Creation Unemployment New Firms φD,2006 -0.482 1.494 -2.078** -2.944 (0.726) (0.544) (0.0250) (0.660) φD,2008 -0.158 3.600 1.373 3.101 (0.949) (0.104) (0.213) (0.534) φD,2009 -0.910 3.942* 0.405 1.735 (0.723) (0.0763) (0.806) (0.697) φD,2010 2.116 3.932 -0.241 3.359 (0.536) (0.295) (0.916) (0.557) φD,2011 1.693 3.312 0.729 -7.386 (0.717) (0.266) (0.815) (0.118) φD,2012 0.470 3.952 -0.257 -0.378 (0.891) (0.159) (0.932) (0.921) City FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Year FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Covariates Yes Yes Yes Yes Observations 49,639 49,636 49,649 48,878 R-squared 0.252 0.145 0.347 0.278 Significance level: *** significant at the 1% level; ** significant at the 5% level; * significant at the 10% level. Robust standard errors are clustered at the court level. 4 Table A4: Estimation of the difference between cities not affected by the reform and cities that experienced a rise in the distance to the labor court (Differences-in-differences, regression-adjusted, excluding non-treatable cities, Multilevel mixed effects). Job Destruction Job Creation Unemployment New Firms φI,2006 -0.443 1.788 -0.218 -5.569** (0.979) (1.385) (0.884) (2.260) φI,2008 -0.522 -0.950 -1.185 1.428 (0.992) (1.402) (0.896) (2.292) φI,2009 -1.065 -4.647*** -0.644 -2.079 (0.965) (1.364) (0.870) (2.220) φI,2010 -2.778*** -4.839*** -0.821 -2.695 (0.964) (1.364) (0.870) (2.219) φI,2011 -2.916*** -4.535*** 0.552 -3.648 (0.964) (1.363) (0.869) (2.219) φI,2012 -4.338*** -5.749*** 0.248 -4.793** (0.965) (1.364) (0.870) (2.221) City RE Yes Yes Yes Yes Year FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Court × Year RE Yes Yes Yes Yes Covariates Yes Yes Yes Yes Observations 49,640 49,640 49,636 48,768 Significance level: *** significant at the 1% level; ** significant at the 5% level; * significant at the 10% level. 5 Table A5: Estimation of the difference between cities not affected by the reform and cities that experienced a fall in the distance to the labor court (Differences-in-differences, regression-adjusted, excluding non-treatable cities, Multilevel mixed effects). Job Destruction Job Creation Unemployment New Firms φD,2006 -0.375 2.255 -3.312 -1.943 (2.347) (3.297) (2.251) (6.220) φD,2008 -1.281 3.565 0.0155 4.167 (2.377) (3.341) (2.277) (6.287) φD,2009 -0.513 2.648 -0.665 2.159 (2.272) (3.190) (2.180) (6.033) φD,2010 1.473 5.370* -1.650 4.158 (2.270) (3.188) (2.179) (6.030) φD,2011 0.249 2.045 -0.967 -7.222 (2.271) (3.189) (2.180) (6.033) φD,2012 -0.823 4.029 -1.853 0.562 (2.271) (3.189) (2.180) (6.033) City RE Yes Yes Yes Yes Year FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Court × Year RE Yes Yes Yes Yes Covariates Yes Yes Yes Yes Observations 42,891 42,891 42,901 42,228 Significance level: *** significant at the 1% level; ** significant at the 5% level; * significant at the 10% level. 6 Conditional Differences-in-Differences Table A6: Diagnosis of the matching process: Average standardized bias and number of biased variables at 5% (including non-treatable cities). Increased Distance Reduced Distance Algorithm Average Bias №. Biased Var. Average Bias №. Biased Var. Before Matching 4.64 2 7.27 2 EK 2.89 0 7.28 2 GK 3.81 2 7.28 2 N3 0.74 0 5.33 2 CBPS 0.05 0 0.03 0 Table A7: Estimation of the difference between cities not affected by the reform and cities that ex- perienced a rise in the distance to the labor court (Conditional differences-in-differences, regression- adjusted, including non-treatable cities). Job Destruction Job Creation Unemployment New Firms φI,2006 -0.0567 -0.218 -0.326 0.382 (1.018) (1.301) (0.521) (2.495) φI,2008 -0.131 -2.357** -0.129 3.771 (0.722) (1.124) (0.428) (2.797) φI,2009 0.889 -4.932*** -0.0434 -2.812 (1.465) (1.632) (1.071) (2.530) φI,2010 -1.615 -5.333*** 0.239 -2.493 (1.381) (2.016) (1.431) (2.302) φI,2011 -2.490* -4.132* 1.833 -3.329 (1.301) (2.109) (1.778) (2.243) φI,2012 -3.571*** -5.389*** 1.426 -5.031** (1.172) (2.039) (1.814) (2.260) City FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Year FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Covariates Yes Yes Yes Yes Observations 55,395 55,394 55,398 55,397 R-squared 0.227 0.193 0.329 0.291 Significance level: *** significant at the 1% level; ** significant at the 5% level; * significant at the 10% level. Robust standard errors are clustered at the court level. 7 Table A8: Estimation of the difference between cities not affected by the reform and cities that ex- perienced a fall in the distance to the labor court (Conditional differences-in-differences, regression- adjusted, including non-treatable cities). Job Destruction Job Creation Unemployment New Firms φD,2006 0.608 -0.00404 -0.154 -3.451 (1.294) (2.318) (0.890) (6.915) φD,2008 -0.894 3.100 1.294 4.066 (2.298) (2.186) (1.160) (4.833) φD,2009 0.376 1.658 2.727** 0.444 (2.300) (2.411) (1.224) (5.610) φD,2010 3.346 2.186 2.121 3.357 (3.122) (3.278) (1.947) (6.283) φD,2011 2.888 1.622 3.070 -7.466 (4.237) (3.175) (2.500) (5.316) φD,2012 0.695 2.950 3.071 0.885 (3.194) (2.703) (2.576) (4.083) City FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Year FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Covariates Yes Yes Yes Yes Observations 48,869 48,868 48,872 48,871 R-squared 0.266 0.133 0.380 0.282 Significance level: *** significant at the 1% level; ** significant at the 5% level; * significant at the 10% level. Robust standard errors are clustered at the court level. 8 Table A9: Estimation of the difference between cities not affected by the reform and cities that ex- perienced a rise in the distance to the labor court (Conditional differences-in-differences, regression- adjusted, excluding non-treatable cities, including delay in cases at the labor court). Job Destruction Job Creation Unemployment New Firms φI,2006 -0.158 -0.226 -0.311 0.501 (1.002) (1.312) (0.520) (2.508) φI,2008 . . . . φI,2009 0.305 -5.340*** 0.263 -2.362 (1.501) (1.654) (1.169) (2.503) φI,2010 -1.943 -6.033*** 0.492 -2.043 (1.365) (2.030) (1.534) (2.386) φI,2011 -2.706** -4.770** 2.057 -3.400 (1.315) (2.211) (1.874) (2.293) φI,2012 -3.672*** -5.895*** 1.555 -4.783** (1.175) (2.048) (1.898) (2.212) Delay in cases Yes Yes Yes Yes City FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Year FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Covariates Yes Yes Yes Yes Observations 41,837 41,837 41,840 41,839 R-squared 0.230 0.215 0.332 0.264 Significance level: *** significant at the 1% level; ** significant at the 5% level; * signifi- cant at the 10% level. Robust standard errors are clustered at the court level. 9 Table A10: Estimation of the difference between cities not affected by the reform and cities that ex- perienced a fall in the distance to their labor court (Conditional differences-in-differences, regression- adjusted, excluding non-treatable cities, including delay in cases at the labor court). Job Destruction Job Creation Unemployment New Firms φD,2006 0.645 0.0157 -0.0756 -3.203 (1.305) (2.415) (0.917) (6.917) φD,2008 . . . . φD,2009 -0.183 0.642 2.945** 0.0520 (2.379) (2.809) (1.363) (6.062) φD,2010 3.270 0.835 2.293 3.124 (3.094) (3.275) (1.935) (6.209) φD,2011 3.121 0.395 3.231 -7.810 (4.242) (3.429) (2.582) (4.856) φD,2012 1.058 1.608 3.087 0.632 (3.076) (3.044) (2.595) (3.976) Delay in cases Yes Yes Yes Yes City FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Year FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Covariates Yes Yes Yes Yes Observations 36,197 36,197 36,200 36,199 R-squared 0.275 0.145 0.391 0.234 Significance level: *** significant at the 1% level; ** significant at the 5% level; * signifi- cant at the 10% level. Robust standard errors are clustered at the court level. 10 Table A11: Estimation of the difference between cities not affected by the reform and cities that ex- perienced a rise in the distance to the labor court (Conditional differences-in-differences, regression- adjusted, excluding non-treatable cities, 3-nearest neighbor matching algorithm). Job Destruction Job Creation Unemployment New Firms φI,2006 -0.340 -0.665 -0.159 0.989 (1.064) (1.448) (0.542) (2.796) φI,2008 -0.864 -2.254* 0.0661 4.751 (0.794) (1.232) (0.461) (3.230) φI,2009 -0.246 -4.952*** 0.279 -2.290 (1.526) (1.758) (1.096) (2.646) φI,2010 -2.518* -5.966*** 0.239 -2.053 (1.437) (2.085) (1.460) (2.380) φI,2011 -3.662*** -5.147** 1.677 -4.047* (1.383) (2.218) (1.829) (2.432) φI,2012 -4.225*** -6.560*** 1.025 -5.363** (1.256) (2.174) (1.901) (2.504) City FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Year FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Covariates Yes Yes Yes Yes Observations 24,142 24,142 24,142 24,142 R-squared 0.237 0.192 0.340 0.294 Significance level: *** significant at the 1% level; ** significant at the 5% level; * significant at the 10% level. Robust standard errors are clustered at the court level. 11 Table A12: Estimation of the difference between cities not affected by the reform and cities that ex- perienced a fall in the distance to the labor court (Conditional differences-in-differences, regression- adjusted, excluding non-treatable cities, 3-nearest neighbor matching algorithm). Job Destruction Job Creation Unemployment New Firms φD,2006 0.318 -2.345 -0.472 -7.530 (1.766) (3.052) (0.976) (8.456) φD,2008 -1.216 3.284 1.206 -1.972 (2.643) (2.628) (1.328) (7.785) φD,2009 -1.871 1.649 2.883** -6.002 (2.860) (2.954) (1.409) (7.263) φD,2010 1.208 1.834 1.768 -4.766 (3.599) (3.932) (2.132) (8.135) φD,2011 1.251 0.288 1.104 -13.84* (4.756) (3.723) (2.647) (7.535) φD,2012 -0.639 1.072 0.840 -9.122 (3.954) (3.185) (2.874) (5.897) City FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Year FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Covariates Yes Yes Yes Yes Observations 2,927 2,927 2,927 2,927 R-squared 0.292 0.142 0.429 0.254 Significance level: *** significant at the 1% level; ** significant at the 5% level; * significant at the 10% level. Robust standard errors are clustered at the court level. 12 Table A13: Estimation of the difference between cities not affected by the reform and cities that ex- perienced a rise in the distance to the labor court (Conditional differences-in-differences, regression- adjusted, excluding non-treatable cities, Multilevel mixed effects). Job Destruction Job Creation Unemployment New Firms φI,2006 0.482 0.460 -0.448 0.479 (0.888) (1.393) (0.602) (2.684) φI,2008 -0.0243 -2.233** -1.125** 4.586 (0.799) (1.114) (0.457) (2.877) φI,2009 -0.0778 -5.086*** -0.684 -0.637 (1.269) (1.310) (0.647) (2.049) φI,2010 -2.120* -5.739*** -0.747 -0.767 (1.278) (1.725) (1.098) (1.905) φI,2011 -2.600** -5.198*** 0.624 -1.975 (1.182) (1.778) (1.452) (1.787) φI,2012 -3.927*** -6.528*** -0.0754 -3.358** (1.148) (1.756) (1.537) (1.623) City RE Yes Yes Yes Yes Year FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Court × Year RE Yes Yes Yes Yes Covariates Yes Yes Yes Yes Observations 48,752 48,752 48,755 48,754 Significance level: *** significant at the 1% level; ** significant at the 5% level; * significant at the 10% level. 13 Table A14: Estimation of the difference between cities not affected by the reform and cities that ex- perienced a fall in the distance to the labor court (Conditional differences-in-differences, regression- adjusted, excluding non-treatable cities, Multilevel mixed effects). Job Destruction Job Creation Unemployment New Firms φD,2006 0.400 0.332 -1.540 -2.149 (1.407) (2.670) (1.677) (6.788) φD,2008 -0.695 3.195 -0.370 6.541 (2.217) (2.453) (1.083) (4.771) φD,2009 -1.422 0.717 -0.583 2.556 (2.405) (2.228) (1.229) (3.641) φD,2010 2.087 1.099 -1.639 5.029 (2.560) (3.843) (1.563) (5.236) φD,2011 1.635 0.749 -0.834 -6.513 (3.289) (2.857) (3.062) (4.504) φD,2012 0.111 2.078 -1.116 1.995 (2.431) (2.711) (3.026) (3.394) City RE Yes Yes Yes Yes Year FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Court × Year RE Yes Yes Yes Yes Covariates Yes Yes Yes Yes Observations 42,226 42,226 42,229 42,228 Significance level: *** significant at the 1% level; ** significant at the 5% level; * significant at the 10% level. 14 Table A15: Linear estimation of the effect of a change of distance. (No matching-correction, includ- ing non-treatable cities.) Job Destruction Job Creation Unemployment New Firms φ2006 -0.0155 0.0408 0.0177 -0.155** (0.0365) (0.0378) (0.0194) (0.0702) φ2008 -0.0249 -0.0629* -0.00174 -0.0419 (0.0201) (0.0326) (0.0127) (0.0839) φ2009 -0.000262 -0.142*** -0.00908 -0.120* (0.0428) (0.0421) (0.0232) (0.0660) φ2010 -0.0904*** -0.133** -0.0116 -0.134* (0.0290) (0.0528) (0.0302) (0.0751) φ2011 -0.0933*** -0.0967* 0.0323 -0.108* (0.0332) (0.0565) (0.0492) (0.0604) φ2012 -0.0942*** -0.119** 0.0510 -0.212*** (0.0330) (0.0515) (0.0452) (0.0459) City FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Year FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Covariates Yes Yes Yes Yes Observations 57,119 57,116 57,115 56,142 R-squared 0.243 0.156 0.340 0.279 Significance level: *** significant at the 1% level; ** significant at the 5% level; * significant at the 10% level. Robust standard errors are clustered at the court level. 15 Table A16: Linear estimation of the effect of a change of distance. (With matching-correction, including non-treatable cities.) Job Destruction Job Creation Unemployment New Firms φ2006 -0.00746 0.00247 0.0152 -0.0278 (0.0324) (0.0327) (0.0184) (0.0658) φ2008 -0.00998 -0.109*** -0.0118 -0.00818 (0.0202) (0.0269) (0.00969) (0.0840) φ2009 0.00737 -0.176*** -0.0206 -0.0907 (0.0435) (0.0358) (0.0234) (0.0647) φ2010 -0.0858*** -0.160*** -0.0197 -0.106 (0.0252) (0.0501) (0.0270) (0.0766) φ2011 -0.0868*** -0.140*** 0.0202 -0.0620 (0.0318) (0.0493) (0.0496) (0.0563) φ2012 -0.0772** -0.144*** 0.0448 -0.182*** (0.0314) (0.0478) (0.0466) (0.0421) City FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Year FE Yes Yes Yes Yes Covariates Yes Yes Yes Yes Observations 56,119 56,118 56,122 56,121 R-squared 0.229 0.188 0.332 0.290 Significance level: *** significant at the 1% level; ** significant at the 5% level; * significant at the 10% level. Robust standard errors are clustered at the court level. Introduction Literature The institutional context The French labor market French Labor Courts Overview of the 2008 Reform Potential impacts of the reform Data Information and units of observation Descriptive Statistics Empirical Analysis Differences-in-Differences Method Results Conditional Differences-in-Differences Matching The Results of Conditional Differences-in-differences Linear Impact of the Distance Limitations Conclusion and Discussion work_fjeze6dlafhpfhhbneu6hs3ku4 ---- S074808141700011Xjra 33..39 ESSAY ROUNDTABLE god the judge and human justice randy beck Justice Thomas O. Marshall Chair of Constitutional Law, University of Georgia School of Law KEYWORDS: justice, mercy, retribution, punishment, reward The biblical authors often portray God as a royal judge who brings justice to a fallen creation. This portrayal analogizes God’s role in governing humanity to the role played by judges in human legal systems. The divine judge, like human judges, investigates and evaluates conduct, measuring human acts against applicable laws. Like human judges, he fashions punishments and rewards to accom- plish justice in light of the conduct disclosed. The recurring biblical portrayal of God as a judge invites reection on the relationship between divine and human justice: How far should the analogy between God and human judges be taken? Should judges “imitate God, in whose Seat they sit?”1 Or might the differences between God and human judges mean that some judgments are appropriate only for God to impose?2 This essay considers what insights divine justice might offer for human law. I begin by analyzing three biblical accounts of divine justice: Jesus’s story of the rich man and Lazarus, the punishment of King Uzziah for usurping priestly functions, and the reward bestowed on Jesus for resisting the devil’s temptations. In each account, God implements a sophisticated form of retributive justice, artistically applying the principle “as he has done it shall be done to him” (Leviticus 24:19).3 This biblical understanding of divine justice can help us understand and evaluate human legal systems. biblical portrayals of divine justice The Rich Man and Lazarus In Luke’s gospel, Jesus tells the story of the rich man and Lazarus (Luke 16:19–31). The narrative concerns a rich man who feasts daily. He routinely walks past a poor beggar named Lazarus but never stops to help. Jesus artistically describes how the rich man and Lazarus effectively trade places in the afterlife. As illustrated in the table below, the account reects a sustained parallelism between what the rich man does (or fails to do) in this life and what happens in the life to come: 1 Francis Bacon, Of Judicature, in FRANCIS BACON, THE ESSAYS 316, 320 (1625) (Scholars Press 1971). 2 Vladimir Soloviev, On the Death Penalty, in 2 THE TEACHINGS OF MODERN CHRISTIANITY ON LAW, POLITICS AND HUMAN NATURE 430 (John Witte, Jr. & Frank S. Alexander, eds., 2007). 3 Biblical quotations come from the English Standard Version. Journal of Law and Religion 32, no. 1 (2017): 33–39 © Center for the Study of Law and Religion at Emory University doi:10.1017/jlr.2017.11 journal of law and religion 33 at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/jlr.2017.11 Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:29, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/jlr.2017.11 https://www.cambridge.org/core This life The afterlife The rich man lives luxuriously. Lazarus rests in Abraham’s bosom. Lazarus is hungry and covered with sores. The rich man is thirsty and tormented by ame. Lazarus longs for crumbs from the rich man’s table. The rich man longs for drops of water from Lazarus’s nger. Lazarus begs, but the rich man fails to help. The rich man begs, but Lazarus cannot help. The rich man is presumably well known; Lazarus is overlooked. Lazarus has a name; the rich man’s name is never mentioned. The Mosaic “eye-for-an-eye” principle assumes a simple scenario in which one individual assaults another. In Jesus’s story, the rich man commits no act of violence. He hardly notices Lazarus. Does retributive justice apply to wrongful inaction? The Proverbs anticipated this question and offered a picture of retributive justice in circumstances like these: “Whoever closes his ear to the cry of the poor will himself call out and not be answered” (Proverbs 21:13). Jesus’s story offers an extended illustration of the proverb, clarifying how divine justice responds to indifference in the face of suffering. Uzziah and the Priests The author of Chronicles tells the story of Uzziah, who became king of Judah in place of his father (2 Chronicles 26). “[A]s long as he sought the LORD, God made him prosper.” As an old man, how- ever, Uzziah’s pride led to his downfall. Uzziah entered the temple to burn incense, where he was confronted by Azariah and a company of priests: “It is not for you, Uzziah, to burn incense to the LORD, but for the priests, the sons of Aaron, who are con- secrated to burn incense. Go out of the sanctuary, for you have done wrong, and it will bring you no honor from the LORD God.” Then Uzziah was angry. Now he had a censer in his hand to burn incense, and when he became angry with the priests, leprosy broke out on his forehead in the presence of the priests in the house of the LORD, by the altar of incense. And Azariah the chief priest and all the priests looked at him, and behold, he was leprous in his forehead! And they rushed him out quickly, and he himself hurried to go out, because the LORD had struck him. And King Uzziah was a leper to the day of his death, and being a leper lived in a separate house, for he was excluded from the house of the LORD. And Jotham his son was over the king’s household, governing the people of the land. (2 Chronicles 26:18b–21) From one perspective, we could say that Uzziah was unwilling to let God rule in God’s “house,” so the punishment made it impossible for Uzziah to rule in his own “house.”4 From a broader perspec- tive, however, Uzziah’s punishment reects the harm inicted on Israel’s communal life. Israel’s kings were to be descendants of David, from the tribe of Judah. Temple functions were reserved for priests from the tribe of Levi. By assigning the kingship and priesthood to different tribes, God implemented a form of separation of powers, ensuring a degree of partition between religion and politics. In his pride, Uzziah challenged this divided structure, seeking a place at the center of both political and religious life. Since Uzziah sought to usurp religious authority God had not given him, he was effectively deprived of the political authority God had given him. 4 Many thanks to Beth Beck for this observation. randy beck 34 journal of law and religion at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/jlr.2017.11 Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:29, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/jlr.2017.11 https://www.cambridge.org/core Uzziah’s usurpation of priestly functions rested on an implicit claim that he was morally t to serve in the temple. Divine justice not only undermined the king’s objective, but also responded to the implied assertion. The authority of the high priest was represented by a gold plate worn on his forehead, engraved with the words “Holy to the LORD” (Exodus 28:36–38). In response to Uzziah’s misconduct, God gave the king leprosy, a sign of uncleanness, in the same location as the high priest’s inscription. Jesus’s Resistance to Temptation Discussions of “justice” often focus on punishment, but giving people what they deserve also involves rewards for meritorious conduct. As illustrated in the table below, Matthew’s gospel dis- plays this sort of divine justice, artistically linking Jesus’s virtuous conduct near the beginning of his public ministry, when he resists the devil’s temptations (Matthew 4:8–10), with the honors bestowed on Jesus as the gospel draws to a close (Matthew 28:16–20). Matthew 4:8–10 Matthew 28:16–20 The devil takes Jesus to a very high “mountain.” The disciples meet Jesus on a “mountain.” Jesus refuses to “worship” the devil. The disciples “worship” Jesus. The devil offers to “give” Jesus “all” the kingdoms of the world. Jesus says “all” authority in heaven and on earth has been “given” to him. These passages describe the rst and last times Jesus ascends a mountain in Matthew’s gospel, narrative details with structural signicance.5 The passages are linked by the theme of proper wor- ship. Jesus rejects the devil’s temptation based on the Deuteronomic principle that one must wor- ship God alone. The gospel subtly reveals Jesus’s divine identity when the disciples worship him at the end of the book. Comparison of the accounts also reveals parallelism between the inducement offered by Satan and the honor bestowed on Jesus after he triumphs over the cross. The devil offered to “give” Jesus “all” the kingdoms of the world and their glory. Because Jesus resisted temptation, God “gives” him “all” authority in heaven and on earth, a reward like, but greater than, the inducement offered by Satan. jesus and the lex talionis In the Sermon on the Mount from Matthew’s gospel, Jesus seems to call into question the talionic “eye-for-an-eye” principle from the law of Moses: You have heard that it was said, “An eye for an eye and a tooth for a tooth.” But I say to you, Do not resist the one who is evil. But if anyone slaps you on the right cheek, turn to him the other also. And if anyone would sue you and take your tunic, let him have your cloak as well. And if anyone forces you to go one mile, go with him two miles. (Matthew 5:38–41) 5 WARREN A. GAGE & STEPHEN P. CARPENTER, A LITERARY GUIDE TO THE LIFE OF CHRIST IN MATTHEW, MARK, AND LUKE-ACTS: HOW THE SYNOPTIC EVANGELISTS TELL THE STORY OF JESUS 21–24 (St. Andrews House 2014) (digital pub- lication through Logos Bible Software). god the judge and human justice journal of law and religion 35 at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/jlr.2017.11 Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:29, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/jlr.2017.11 https://www.cambridge.org/core This passage has led some Christians to conclude that “Jesus explicitly repudiated the lex talionis.”6 If Jesus in fact rejected the talionic principle, that could call into question the broader norm of retributive justice. Several other passages from the Sermon on the Mount, however, assume that God as judge enforces the demands of retributive justice. Consider a familiar petition from the Lord’s Prayer: “forgive us our debts, as we also have forgiven our debtors.” Jesus elaborates: “For if you forgive others their trespasses, your heavenly Father will also forgive you, but if you do not forgive others their trespasses, neither will your Father forgive your trespasses” (Matthew 6:14–15). Jesus’s teach- ing rests on a talionic understanding of divine justice; God treats people the same way they treat others. Another familiar passage makes a similar point: “Judge not, that you be not judged. For with the judgment you pronounce you will be judged, and with the measure you use it will be mea- sured to you” (Matthew 7:1–2). Retributive justice may also underlie a number of the Beatitudes. For instance, “Blessed are the merciful, for they shall receive mercy” seems perfectly retributive; the blessed are treated the same way they treat others (Matthew 5:7). Considering the context, then, we should read Jesus’s teaching concerning the talionic principle against a background assumption of divine retribution. In place of “[a]n eye for an eye and a tooth for a tooth” from the law of Moses, Jesus instructs “[d]o not resist the one who is evil,” offering three illustrations. Each illustration, on closer examination, involves a connection between the talionic principle and Jesus’s suggested response. If one person slaps another on the cheek, the talionic principle would call for a retaliatory slap on the aggressor’s cheek. When Jesus says “turn to him the other [cheek] also,” he urges the victim to accept the punishment the aggressor deserves. Similarly, if someone evil sues for a person’s tunic, the talionic response would be to demand the plaintiff’s garment in return. Instead, Jesus tells the victim to “let him have your cloak as well,” accepting the retributive punishment earned by the wrongdoer. The talionic response to being forced to walk a mile would be to force the aggressor to walk a mile in a different direction. Jesus instead asks the victim to “go with him two miles.” Jesus does not question the justice of retribution, but asks his followers to set aside the demands of justice or, more precisely, to fulll the demands of justice on behalf of those who wrong them. Jesus’s teaching here provides a picture of His own ministry as explained in other parts of the New Testament. Jesus’s death fullled the demands of justice on behalf of those who were his enemies (Romans 3:21–26, 5:6–10). We should not be surprised, then, that echoes of this passage reverberate through Matthew’s account of Jesus’s trial and execution. We see Jesus slapped on the face during his trial before the high priest (Matthew 26:67–68). We see him stripped of his garments by Roman soldiers (Matthew 27:31, 35). We see him forced to walk from Gethsemane to Caiaphas, then from Caiaphas to Pilate, and then from Pilate to Golgotha (Matthew 26:57, 27:2, 31). Jesus does not reject retributive justice in the Sermon on the Mount, but instead draws novel implications from the assumption of divine retribution. The talionic principle gives retributive jus- tice a backward looking focus. Jesus gives retributive justice a forward looking focus in the Golden Rule: “So whatever you wish that others would do to you, do also to them, for this is the Law and the Prophets” (Matthew 7:12). Christians are not to treat others the way others treated them in the past; instead they must treat others the way they would like to be treated in the future. 6 UNITED METHODIST CHURCH, BOOK OF RESOLUTIONS, 2004 (2004), resolution 246. randy beck 36 journal of law and religion at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/jlr.2017.11 Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:29, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/jlr.2017.11 https://www.cambridge.org/core god’s justice and human justice Having examined biblical depictions of divine justice, we are now in a position to consider impli- cations for human law. We might analogize this exercise to the use economists make of the idea of perfect competition. A model of perfect competition assists in economic analysis because “the oper- ation of a purely competitive economy provides us with a standard, or norm, against which the efciency of the real-world economy can be compared and evaluated.”7 Similarly, we can describe perfect justice by reference to the characteristics of God as Judge and the relationship between acts and consequences in his judgments. These features of perfect justice can then help us evaluate human legal systems and identify shortcomings and limitations of human law. God’s Character as a Model for Human Judges Biblical narratives about divine justice rest on the foundation of God’s character. Attributes that make God an ideal judge can be used to evaluate human judges. King Jehoshaphat makes this logic explicit when he instructs the judges of Judah: “Consider what you do, for you judge not for man but for the LORD. He is with you in giving judgment. Now then, let the fear of the LORD be upon you. Be careful what you do, for there is no injustice with the LORD our God, or par- tiality or taking bribes” (2 Chronicles 19). God is just, so judges must be just. God is impartial, so they should be impartial. God will not take a bribe, so neither should they. Human Judges Lack God’s Knowledge and Power Although we want human judges to imitate God in certain respects, there are many ways in which human judges differ from God. These differences affect the reliability of human judgments and the capacity of human institutions to accomplish complete justice. Human judges lack God’s full knowledge of past and future events. They often base their legal conclusions on factual ndings later found to be inaccurate. God also differs from human judges with respect to the power and resources at his command. The limited power of human courts bounds the sorts of judgments they can impose and, hence, the objectives human justice can pursue. A biblical understanding of our moral obligations—perfect love of God and neighbor—compels a distinction between moral- ity and law. Human justice necessarily falls short of divine justice both in the range of obligations enforced and the accuracy of determinations concerning whether those obligations have been violated. Perfect Retribution and the Theory of Punishment How should governments decide what punishments to inict? Retributivists argue that offenders should be given the punishments they deserve. They suggest that viewing punishment as a means to an end, without reference to any notion of desert, could result in excessive punishments. Consequentialists argue that punishment should produce desirable consequences, such as deter- rence or incapacitation or reformation. A consistent theory of retribution, they believe, calls for the state to inict suffering on the morally culpable, even when no social good results. 7 CAMPBELL R. MCCONNELL & WILLIAM HENRY POPE, ECONOMICS: PRINCIPLES, PROBLEMS, AND POLICIES 137 (4th Canadian ed. 1987). god the judge and human justice journal of law and religion 37 at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/jlr.2017.11 Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:29, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/jlr.2017.11 https://www.cambridge.org/core Discussions between retributivists and consequentialists often reference the talionic principle, understood to embody a retributive theory of punishment. But while divine justice is retributive, it does not follow that Christians should side with retributivists over consequentialists in debates about human law. Our examination of biblical justice led to the conclusion that human government can enforce only a small subset of the obligations imposed by divine law. Human government pos- sesses limited capacity and resources, and must leave much wrongdoing unaddressed. In deciding how to direct the coercive efforts of government, plenty of room exists for consequentialist consid- erations, even if one believes in retribution as the ideal of justice. The Unsatisfactory Results of Proportionality Review The US Supreme Court has interpreted two provisions of the Constitution to require some degree of proportionality between an offense and the resulting punishment, the Eighth Amendment with respect to criminal sentencing8 and the Due Process Clause in connection with punitive damages.9 The Court’s proportionality jurisprudence will always be problematic. We can see the problem by comparing the Court’s attempts at proportionality analysis with the examples of biblical justice dis- cussed above. In the biblical accounts, the punishment was like the offense in some clearly discern- ible way. Our system of justice, however, relies on monetary penalties and imprisonment. These homogenized modes of punishment make it virtually impossible to determine whether the magni- tude of a penalty matches the gravity of the offense. Divine Justice as a Motive for Mercy Some retributivists consider mercy problematic, since clemency involves a departure from the requirements of justice. Saint Augustine addressed this question in a fascinating letter responding to an inquiry from a Roman judge. The provincial governor of Africa, Macedonius, asked why the clergy interceded on behalf of condemned prisoners. He suggested that the church implicated itself in criminal conduct by seeking to prevent just punishment. In response, Augustine offered several arguments for clerical intercession and judicial clemency. Of particular interest, Augustine contended a judge should extend mercy because the judge will one day be judged: “[Y]ou need the mercy which you grant to others.”10 In this respect, he suggested, the judge, the criminal, and the intercessor all stand on common ground: “we intercede, if not as criminals for criminals, at least as sinners for sinners, and, I think, with sinners.”11 Augustine’s letter to Macedonius suggests various limiting principles to cabin judicial clemency. Intercession was apparently limited to offenders who acknowledged their crimes and promised a change of behavior. He also recognized that for some offenders, mercy might do more harm than good. Moreover, he acknowledged that judicial severity can serve important purposes, includ- ing deterrence.12 8 See, e.g., Harmelin v. Michigan, 501 U.S. 957 (1991). 9 See, e.g., State Farm Mutual Automotive Insurance Co. v. Campbell, 538 U.S. 408 (2003). 10 Letter from Augustine to Macedonius (Letter 153), in OLIVER O’DONOVAN & JOAN LOCKWOOD O’DONOVAN, FROM IRENAEUS TO GROTIUS: A SOURCEBOOK IN CHRISTIAN POLITICAL THOUGHT 119, 125 (1999). 11 Id. 12 Id. at 127 (“There is good . . . in your severity which works to secure our tranquility, and there is good in our intercession which works to restrain your severity.”). randy beck 38 journal of law and religion at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/jlr.2017.11 Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:29, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/jlr.2017.11 https://www.cambridge.org/core conclusion Biblical portrayals of God as judge turn out to hold numerous lessons for human law. Not least is the need for humility, as the human judge contemplates the limitations that make it impossible to accomplish more than a pale shadow of the justice of God. god the judge and human justice journal of law and religion 39 at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/jlr.2017.11 Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:29, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/jlr.2017.11 https://www.cambridge.org/core GOD THE JUDGE AND HUMAN JUSTICE Biblical Portrayals of Divine Justice The Rich Man and Lazarus Uzziah and the Priests Jesus's Resistance to Temptation Jesus and the Lex Talionis God's Justice and Human Justice God's Character as a Model for Human Judges Human Judges Lack God's Knowledge and Power Perfect Retribution and the Theory of Punishment The Unsatisfactory Results of Proportionality Review Divine Justice as a Motive for Mercy Conclusion work_fm3o7ymovrhndk25k7epeflwiq ---- artigojosecarlosricardo Justiça de Transição e Poder Judiciário brasileiro - a barreira da Lei de Anistia para a responsabilização dos crimes da ditadura civil-militar no Brasil Ricardo Silveira Castro∗ José Carlos Moreira da Silva Filho∗∗ 1. Introdução Justiça de transição é o termo que designa o conjunto de práticas e mecanismos que devem ser adotados pelos Estados que passam por períodos de conflito (ditaduras, guerras civis e outras situações de prática de violência massiva) e precisam se reestruturar para possibilitar a consolidação da democracia. A atuação das ações transicionais costumam ser divididas em quatro dimensões: as que buscam atender o direito à verdade e à memória, as que pretendem reparar as vítimas dos atos de exceção, as que visam a reforma das instituições e as que objetivam a punição dos agentes estatais que violaram normas de direitos humanos1. O foco desse trabalho é a dimensão ∗ Acadêmico do curso de Direito na Pontifícia Universidade Católica do Rio Grande do Sul. Bolsista de Iniciação Científica PIBIC/CNPQ. Membro do Grupo de Pesquisa CNPq Direito à Verdade e à Memória e Justiça de Transição. E-mail: silveiraricardocastro@gmail.com ∗∗Doutor em Direito das Relações Sociais pela Universidade Federal do Paraná - UFPR; Mestre em Teoria e Filosofia do Direito pela Universidade Federal de Santa Catarina - UFSC; Bacharel em Direito pela Universidade de Brasília - UnB; Professor da Faculdade de Direito da Pontifícia Universidade Católica do Rio Grande do Sul - PUCRS (Programa de Pós-graduação em Ciências Criminais – Mestrado e Doutorado - e Graduação em Direito); Bolsista Produtividade em Pesquisa do CNPq - Nível 2; Vice- Presidente da Comissão de Anistia do Ministério da Justiça; Coordenador do Grupo de Pesquisa CNPq Direito à Verdade e à Memória e Justiça de Transição; Membro-Diretor do Grupo de Estudos sobre Internacionalização do Direito e Justiça de Transição – IDEJUST. E-Mail: josecarlosfilho@terra.com.br 1 Diante da limitação do espaço não pretendemos adentrar aqui na problemática da definição do termo "Justiça de Transição", tema explorado por diferentes estudos, tais como: ARTHUR, Paige. Como as 'transições' reconfiguraram os direitos humanos: uma história conceitual da justiça de transição. In: REÁTEGUI, Félix (org.). Justiça de Transição - manual para a América Latina. Brasília: Comissão de Anisita, Ministério da Justiça; New York: International Center for Transitional Justice, 2011. p.73-133; TEITEL, Ruti. Transitional Justice. New York: Oxford University, 2000; WINTER, Stephen. Towards a unified theory of transitional justice. In: The International Journal of Transitional Justice, Oxford University Press, v.7, n.2, p.224-244, julho 2013; IVERSON, Jens. Transitional justice, jus post bellum and international criminal law: differentiating the usages, history and dynamics. In: The International Journal of Transitional Justice, Oxford University Press, v.7, n.3, p.413-433, novembro 2013; AMBOS, Kai. The Legal Framework of Transitional Justice. In: AMBOS, Kai; LARGE, J.; WIERDA, M. (Eds). Building A Future On Peace And Justice: Studies On Transitional Justice, Conflict Resolution And Development, Berlim, p. 19-103, 2009. Disponível em: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1972143 or http://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.1972143 (Acesso em 07/01/2014); QUINALHA, Renan Honório. Justiça de Transição - contornos do conceito. São Paulo: Outras Expressões; Dobra Editorial, 2013; Revista Anistia Política e Justiça de Transição, Brasília, n.7, jan.- jun. 2012. Como patamar introdutório suficiente para os fins deste artigo, enunciamos a definição adotada em documento produzido pelo Conselho de Segurança da ONU: “A noção de ‘justiça de transição’ que costuma ser a mais problemática da justiça transicional, isto é, a responsabilização. A importância do estudo a respeito da possibilidade jurídica de haver julgamentos voltados à atribuição de responsabilidade criminal aos agentes do regime militar de 1964 está relacionada com a necessidade de se construir uma cultura de respeito e fortalecimento aos direitos humanos pelas forças de segurança pública do Estado Democrático de Direito brasileiro. Na primeira parte do presente trabalho, buscar-se-á apresentar – a partir do contexto político de limitação da transição brasileira – a dificuldade encontrada pelos perseguidos políticos e seus familiares em responsabilizar os agentes do Estado envolvidos em crimes comuns durante a repressão política do regime militar de 1964. Num segundo momento, serão analisados os rumos que a transição brasileira tomou, inclinando-se mais à dimensão da reparação às vítimas da ditadura e menos à responsabilização dos agentes estatais. Mais adiante serão tecidas algumas considerações a respeito da contrariedade existente entre os principais precedentes do Supremo Tribunal Federal que discutiram o tema das transições políticas relacionadas às ditaduras civis-militares que assolaram o Cone Sul na segunda metade do século XX. Por fim, será trazido à baila o tema da vinculação do Brasil e das suas decisões judiciais aos termos da Convenção Americana de Direitos Humanos e à jurisprudência da Corte Interamericana de Direitos Humanos. 2. Os crimes da ditadura brasileira e a anistia de 1979: tentativas frustradas de responsabilização Durante as décadas de 1960 e 1970, no contexto da Guerra Fria, ocorreram diversos golpes de Estado em países da América Latina, dentre os quais, está o Brasil. A ditadura civil-militar que golpeou a Constituição de 1946 - democraticamente discutida no presente relatório compreende o conjunto de processos e mecanismos associados às tentativas da sociedade em chegar a um acordo quanto ao grande legado de abusos cometidos no passado, a fim de assegurar que os responsáveis prestem contas de seus atos, que seja feita a justiça e se conquiste a reconciliação. Tais mecanismos podem ser judiciais e extrajudiciais, com diferentes níveis de envolvimento internacional (ou nenhum), bem como abarcar o juízo de processos individuais, reparações, busca da verdade, reforma institucional, investigação de antecedentes, a destruição de um cargo ou a combinação de todos esses procedimentos” (NAÇÕES UNIDAS – Conselho de Segurança. O Estado de Direito e a justiça de transição em sociedades em conflito ou pós-conflito. Relatório do Secretário Geral S/2004/616. In: Revista Anistia Política e Justiça de Transição, Brasília, n.1, p.320-351, jan.-jun. 2009. p.325). Sobre o tema da Justiça de Transição, conferir: ABRÃO, Paulo. (Org.) ; VIEIRA, Jose Ribas (Org.) ; LOPES, J. R. L. (Org.) ; TORELLY, M. D. (Org.). Dossiê: o que é justiça de transição? In: Revista Anistia Política e Justiça de Transição, Brasília, n.1, p.31-112, jan.-jun. 2009. promulgada - marcou esse período histórico pela cultura do terror instaurada. A perseguição promovida contra os opositores do regime autoritário logo em seguida do golpe revelou a impossibilidade de diálogo democrático e sepultou a liberdade de expressão. O regime militar utilizou-se da estrutura estatal para cometer crimes de lesa- humanidade. O Estado de Exceção criou técnicas de neutralização2 que visavam inverter o cenário decorrente da prática de seus crimes: os agentes policiais e militares passavam de criminosos a defensores da ordem e da lei. É característica do crime de Estado a pretensão de sempre estar justificado. No caso brasileiro, as marcas deixadas pelas técnicas de neutralização são tão profundas que continuam contaminando o entendimento de muitos cidadãos, inclusive com a negação do direito de resistência dos que se opuseram ao plano de poder imposto em 1964. O fenômeno da legalidade autoritária3 relacionado especificamente à ditadura civil-militar é fruto de uma grande preocupação dos golpistas em legitimar suas ações através do campo jurídico. É preciso reconhecer que o Poder Judiciário brasileiro, em geral, foi importante aliado das Forças Armadas na construção do projeto militar autoritário. Essa aliança foi desenvolvida ao longo do período ditatorial, quando o Poder Judiciário reconheceu como “subversivos” os opositores políticos do regime militar, aplicando-lhes penas estabelecidas em leis draconianas. A transição política controlada pelos militares e pelos setores da sociedade que os apoiavam teve início ainda na década de 1970 e foi marcada pela ameaça de um autoritarismo ressurgente. Mesmo assim, a promessa de liberdade em um regime democrático guiou as lutas dos comitês brasileiros pela anistia, que colocaram em 2 O conceito de "técnicas de neutralização" advém dos estudos de Sykes & Matza desenvolvido nos anos 50 a respeito da delinquência juvenil (SYKES, Gresham M.; MATZA, David. Techniques of neutralization: a theory of delinquency. In: American Sociological Review, n.22, 1957, p.664-670) e apontam para a ideia de que a sua utilização neutraliza em determinadas circunstâncias o caráter reprovável do ato violento. Zaffaroni faz uso desses conceitos para analisar os crimes do Estado. A esse respeito, ver: ZAFFARONI, Eugenio Raul. La palabra de los muertos - conferencias de criminologia cautelar. Buenos Aires: EDIAR, 2011. p.447-474 e SILVA FILHO, José Carlos Moreira da . Crimes do Estado e Justiça de Transição. Sistema Penal & Violência, v. 2, p. 22-35, 2010. 3 O conceito está presente no importante estudo de Anthony W. Pereira acerca da judicialização e legalização da repressão no Chile, na Argentina e no Brasil e pode ser estendido não somente para o período autoritário iniciado em 1964, mas também para outros momentos marcantes da história do Brasil nos quais o bacharelismo legalista serviu para dar preferência a tecnicalidades pontuais em detrimento das orientações principiológicas voltadas ao aprofundamento democrático e ao fortalecimento dos direitos humanos. Ver: PEREIRA, Anthony W. Ditadura e repressão: o autoritarismo e o estado de direito no Brasil, no Chile e na Argentina. São Paulo: Paz e Terra, 2010. discussão na sociedade civil a importância da anistia para a retomada do exercício de direitos fundamentais pelos brasileiros perseguidos pelo regime de exceção. A anistia reclamada veio em 1979, com a promulgação da Lei Nº 6.683. Repleta de distorções, a Lei de Anistia registrava, a grosso modo, um “perdão” recíproco: opressores e oprimidos estariam anistiados. É necessário enfatizar que tal instrumento normativo surge no contexto de uma ditadura militar que seguia comandada por um general e que havia recebido das mãos do seu antecessor, também um general, um Congresso Nacional desfigurado pelo pacote de abril, instituído em 1977 com base no mais virulento dos Atos Institucionais, o AI-5. O Congresso foi fechado por 15 dias e a forma da sua composição foi alterada, aumentando a base de sustentação parlamentar da ditadura e criando, inclusive, a figura do “senador biônico”. Tal esclarecimento é fundamental para que se compreenda a inviabilidade de quaisquer ações naquele momento que buscassem contestar a extensão da anistia aos agentes da repressão estatal. A visualização dessa realidade mostra-se importante na medida em que não é incomum encontrar-se o argumento de que a Lei de Anistia deveria ter sido questionada no seu tempo e não depois. Ocorre que, embora houvesse um processo de abertura política em andamento, em 1979, ainda era muito marcante o controle do regime ditatorial. Contudo, os magistrados do Supremo Tribunal Federal - durante o julgamento da Arguição de Descumprimento de Preceito Fundamental Nº 153 - ignoraram o contexto político existente no período posterior à promulgação da Lei de Anistia para corroborar o argumento de que uma discussão atual daquele instrumento normativo representaria uma “revisão da história” que afrontaria os valores constitucionais vigentes desde 1988. Argumentou-se, em linhas gerais, que se antes não houve possibilidade de enfrentamento da anistia aos agentes da ditadura porque se vivia uma incipiente abertura democrática, hoje esse caminho restou obstaculizado por conta do longo período de tempo (mais de trinta anos) que se passou desde o fim do Estado ditatorial. Em que pese a ameaça do governo militar ter restringido consideravelmente a ação dos perseguidos e de seus familiares na busca pelo esclarecimento de crimes e abusos de autoridade, o fato é que houve algumas tentativas de acionamento do Poder Judiciário após a edição da Lei de Anistia que visavam a defesa dos direitos fundamentais escrachados pelo império da força. Na seara criminal, destacam-se duas batalhas jurídicas travadas antes de 1988: a primeira na Justiça Estadual do Rio Grande do Sul por conta do assassinato do sargento do exército Manoel Raymundo Soares; e a segunda no Superior Tribunal Militar pela tortura do perseguido político Milton Coelho de Carvalho. O militar Manoel Raymundo Soares foi encontrado boiando com as mãos amarradas no Rio do Jacuí no dia 24 de agosto de 1966. Conforme consta no inquérito policial militar que investigou os fatos, Manoel desertou e foi expulso do exército em 1964, a partir de quando passou a viver na clandestinidade. No ano de 1966 o sargento foi recolhido à prisão na Ilha do Presídio por ter sido abordado com panfletos que veiculavam críticas ao governo militar. Mesmo diante do conjunto probatório que apontava para a responsabilidade de agentes do DOPS e da polícia pela prática de tortura e pelo homicídio, o delegado concluiu o procedimento de investigação preliminar sem indiciar ninguém. O caso ganhou repercussão depois que o Promotor de Justiça Paulo Cláudio Tovo decidiu denunciar três policiais pelo homicídio, contrariando a conclusão duvidosa do inquérito4. O juiz de primeiro grau decidiu negar o pedido de pronúncia dos envolvidos por considerar as provas insuficientes5; tempos depois, em 1975, o Tribunal confirmaria esse entendimento para inviabilizar a punição dos agentes denunciados6. De igual modo, Milton Coelho de Carvalho, a época aposentado da Petrobras, foi preso no dia 20 de Fevereiro de 1976 em Aracajú (Sergipe) acusado de ser ligado ao Partido Comunista Brasileiro. A prisão arbitrária fazia parte da “Operação Cajueiro” que foi fruto dos esforços do DOI-CODI, do DOPS e da Polícia Federal. No cárcere, por causa dos procedimentos adotados na tortura, Milton perdeu a visão. O processo para averiguação da responsabilidade dos agentes do estado e sua respectiva punição 4 Ver o famoso "Relatório Tovo" em publicação especial organizada pelo Tribunal Regional Federal da 4a. Região em 2008: ASSUMPÇÃO, Eliane Maria Salgado (org.). O Direito na História: o caso das mãos amarradas. Porto Alegre: TRF 4a. Região, 2008. 5 Cópia dos originais da denúncia oferecida pelo Ministério Público podem ser visualizadas no site: http://digital.canaleletronico.net/maosamarradas/denuncia/index.html (Acesso em 07/01/2014). Ver também a descrição do caso no Relatório da Comissão de Mortos e Desaparecidos Políticos: BRASIL. Secretaria Especial dos Direitos Humanos. Comissão Especial sobre Mortos e Desaparecidos Políticos. Direito à verdade e à memória. Brasília: Secretaria Especial dos Direitos Humanos, 2007. p.75-77. 6 RIO GRANDE DO SUL. Tribunal de Justiça. Câmara Criminal Especial. Recurso Crime n.16.336. Negado provimento em 01/10/1975. Relator: Cristovam Daiello Moreira. Os autos do processo estão arquivados no Memorial do Judiciário do Rio Grande do Sul - TJRS, e para consultá-los é preciso marcar hora e comparecer pessoalmente ao arquivo. transcorreu, em 1980, no Superior Tribunal Militar e na ocasião representou a primeira aplicação da Lei de Anistia como “perdão recíproco”: aqueles que cegaram Milton estavam perdoados7. Além desses dois casos que provocaram o Poder Judiciário a se manifestar antes de 1988 (durante o regime de exceção, portanto), é preciso mencionar outras duas situações que – mesmo ocorrendo após a vigência da Constituição Cidadã – demonstram uma continuidade da ordem estabelecida em 1964: a tentativa do Ministério Público de São Paulo de abrir um inquérito civil para apurar, em 1992, a morte do jornalista Vladimir Herzog e a tentativa de reabrir a investigação do caso Riocentro, em 1996, no Superior Tribunal Militar. Em ambos os casos houve o indeferimento dos pleitos pela mesma razão: incidência da anistia “bilateral” de 19798. O curioso é que, no segundo caso, referente ao atentado ocorrido em 1981 no Riocentro, mesmo reconhecendo indícios de autoria de militares no crime, os Ministros do STM – agindo em desacordo com a própria Lei Nº 6.683/1979 – justificaram o arquivamento do procedimento pela incidência da anistia a crimes cometidos após 1979. A construção de uma “anistia pra frente” representou um verdadeiro estelionato jurídico que contribuiu para fortalecer a noção de que – no Brasil – não haveria responsabilização dos agentes do estado de exceção: como pensar em punir os crimes de tortura, sequestro e homicídio ocorridos antes de 1979 se sobre aqueles que ocorreram depois (como o atentado ao Riocentro) também incidia – legitimamente, conforme o poder Judiciário – a malfadada causa de extinção da punibilidade? Assim, seja antes, seja depois do estabelecimento da ordem democrática pela Constituição de 1988 a tentativa de se construir o pilar da “responsabilização” no 7 JOSÉ, Otto. Os torturadores anistiados – como está sendo aplicada a Lei de Anistia. Movimento, São Paulo, abr. 1980 apud TELES, Janaína de Almeida. As disputas pela interpretação da Lei de Anistia de 1979. In: Idéias. São Paulo, n.1, jan./jun., 2010. p.12. Disponível em:http://www.ifch.unicamp.br/ojs/index.php/ideias/issue/view/2/showToc (Acesso em 07/01/2014). 8 A decisão de trancar o inquérito policial do caso Herzog veio da Quarta câmara do Tribunal de Justiça de São Paulo (SÃO PAULO. Tribunal de Justiça. Habeas Corpus n. 131.798-3/2. Relator Péricles Piza) e foi mantida pelo Superior Tribunal de Justiça (SUPERIOR TRIBUNAL DE JUSTIÇA. Recurso Especial n.33.782-7-SP, j.18/08/1993, 5a Turma, unânime, Relator Ministro José Dantas). Já a decisão de trancar as investigações do caso Riocentro com base na Lei de Anistia foi tomada pelo Superior Tribunal Militar em 1988, quando declarou de ofício a extinção da punibilidade dos autores (Representação n. 1.067-7/DF) e quando negou em 1996 novo pedido de abertura da investigação (Representação Criminal n. 4-0/DF). Maiores detalhes sobre ambos os casos podem ser vistos em: SANTOS, Roberto Lima; BREGA FILHO, Vladimir. Os reflexos da "judicialização" da repressão política no Brasil no seu engajamento com os postulados da justiça de transição. In: Revista Anistia Política e Justiça de Transição. Brasília, n.1, p.152-177, jan./jun. 2009. processo transicional brasileiro sempre esteve presente como reivindicação dos que sofreram com os atos de exceção. No entanto, como se constatou, os termos da interpretação dada ao instituto da anistia impediram qualquer análise de mérito que viabilizasse alguma providência no sentido da investigação e da responsabilização. Somente após a virada do século, a partir de 2008, é que houve uma nova mobilização, por parte de organismos da sociedade civil e de órgãos vinculados ao Estado, que buscou questionar a validade da interpretação da anistia como “acordo bilateral” perante o Supremo Tribunal Federal9. O foco deste artigo é justamente averiguar as contradições da postura do Supremo Tribunal Federal – enquanto órgão máximo do Poder Judiciário – acerca dos temas envolvendo a justiça de transição, precipuamente no que tange ao aspecto da possibilidade de persecução criminal dos crimes de lesa-humanidade cometidos pelos agentes do Estado ditatorial. Para tanto, serão analisadas as contradições existentes em cinco precedentes do Egrégio Tribunal: a ADPF Nº.153, a ADPF Nº 130, a Extradição Nº 974, a Extradição Nº 1.150 e a Extradição Nº 1.228. Na sequência, o foco recairá sobre a contradição da Suprema Corte quanto à interpretação da Convenção Americana de Direitos Humanos e dos precedentes da Corte Interamericana de Direitos Humanos. Antes disso, no entanto, a fim de melhor esclarecer o contexto que deu oportunidade a essas discussões, se fará no próximo item uma breve reflexão acerca do caminho 9 No dia 31 de julho de 2008 a Comissão de Anistia organizou uma audiência pública no prédio sede do Ministério da Justiça em Brasília para discutir as possibilidades jurídicas de julgamento dos torturadores que atuaram em prol do governo ditatorial. A reação da imprensa foi imediata e incessante, e, apesar da tentativa inicial de desqualificar o debate, pautou o tema com elevada frequência em jornais, revistas e outros meios de massa. Artigos a favor e contra a possibilidade do julgamento eram publicados e não paravam de surgir nas páginas dos principais jornais do país. Até então este parecia um assunto proibido. O então Presidente do Conselho Federal da OAB, Cezar Britto, compareceu à audiência e meses depois, sob a influência da discussão, mobilizou o Conselho e propôs, com a assinatura de Fábio Konder Comparato, a Argüição de Descumprimento de Preceito Fundamental Nº 153 no STF. Importante também mencionar a corajosa e importante sentença do juiz Gustavo Santini Teodoro, de outubro de 2008, confirmada pelo Tribunal de Justiça paulista em agosto de 2012, e que, embora só tenha efeitos declarativos, foi a primeira manifestação judicial que reconheceu explicitamente um ex-agente público brasileiro como torturador: o Coronel Carlos Alberto Brilhante Ustra, apontado em dezenas de relatos de ex-perseguidos como torturador e que foi comandante da temida Operação Bandeirante em São Paulo na década de 70. Esquentando ainda mais o ambiente para o julgamento da ADPF Nº 153 no STF, em janeiro de 2010 a Secretaria Especial de Direitos Humanos lança o III Plano Nacional de Direitos Humanos, inaugurando uma Diretriz inexistente nos planos anteriores, aquela que cuida do Direito à Memória e à Verdade. Entre outras deliberações, o Plano propugnou a instituição de uma Comissão Nacional da Verdade, que veio a ser constituída em 2012, e uma série de outras políticas públicas em torno da memória, dano espaço para as opiniões desfavoráveis ao bloqueio da Lei de anistia quanto à investigação e responsabilização dos crimes de lesa humanidade praticados pelos agentes da ditadura. adotado pelo Brasil em sua transição política, mostrando que o motor desse processo foi a preocupação em reparar as vítimas dos atos de exceção. 3. Mais reparação, menos responsabilização A Constituição Federal de 1988 representou uma conquista para o processo de democratização iniciado após a Lei de Anistia de 1979, mas isso não fez dela um instrumento capaz de romper com a cultura autoritária impregnada nas instituições estatais durante os vinte e um anos de vigência do estado de exceção10. Aliás, para criar possibilidades reais de rompimento com a estrutura autoritária é que os mecanismos transicionais atuam em quatro frentes de combate ao legado de repressão: a busca pela verdade e pela memória, a reforma das instituições, a reparação às vítimas e a responsabilização dos crimes cometidos com a violação de direitos humanos. É preciso dizer que no enfrentamento desse legado autoritário não há um percurso “certo” ou “errado”, pois cada país possui suas peculiaridades que necessariamente resultarão em uma postura própria diante da necessidade de se optar pelos meios que serão utilizados para o enfrentamento do legado autoritário. No caso específico do Brasil, é possível perceber que grande parte dos esforços dispensados voltaram-se para a promoção da reparação às vítimas. O próprio texto constitucional que instaurou o Estado Democrático de Direito elencou – no Art. 8º do Ato das Disposições Constitucionais Transitórias (ADCT) - a reparação aos atingidos pelos atos de exceção como imperativo necessário para o restabelecimento de uma ordem legítima. A execução desse mandamento constitucional operacionalizou-se pelo trabalho organizado de duas comissões de reparação: a Comissão Especial de Mortos e Desaparecidos Políticos, vinculada à Secretaria Especial de Direitos Humanos da Presidência da República e a Comissão de Anistia, vinculada ao Ministério da Justiça. A Comissão Especial de Mortos e Desaparecidos Políticos foi criada pela Lei Nº. 9.140/1995 e recebeu a incumbência de reconhecer as pessoas desaparecidas, envidar esforços para localizar os restos mortais dos perseguidos políticos desaparecidos e 10 Como destaca de modo perspicaz Cristiano Paixão (PAIXÃO, Cristiano. A constituição em disputa: transição ou ruptura? In: SEELAENDER, Airton (Org.) História do Direito e construção do Estado. São Paulo: Quartier Latin, 2012. no prelo), a partir das eleições de 1986 e mais intensamente com a instalação da constituinte tornou-se nítida a disputa em torno do significado da Constituição, seja no conflito em torno dos procedimentos adotados pelos constituintes para elaborarem o texto, seja nos esforços de defini-la como o resultado de uma ruptura ou de uma continuidade com o regime de força. também emitir pareceres quanto aos pedidos de indenização formulados pelos familiares, orientando suas ações pelo “princípio de reconciliação e de pacificação nacional”. Enfatize-se que foi por meio desse instrumento normativo que o ordenamento jurídico pátrio reconheceu, pela primeira vez, a responsabilidade objetiva do Estado pela morte e pelo desaparecimento forçado de opositores políticos, durante o regime militar11. Já a Comissão de Anistia foi criada pela MP Nº 2.151/2001, depois convertida na Lei Nº 10.559/2002 e sua função é reparar os perseguidos políticos pelas várias circunstâncias que lhes geraram prejuízos (patrimoniais e extra-patrimoniais): torturas, prisões arbitrárias, demissões, transferências de serviço por razões políticas, sequestros, compelimentos à clandestinidade e ao exílio, banimentos, expurgos estudantis, monitoramentos ilícitos, etc. A reparação aos perseguidos políticos prevista na Lei Nº 10.559 inclui: direito à declaração de condição de anistiado político; direito à reparação econômica; direito à contagem – para todos os efeitos – do tempo em que o perseguido político foi obrigado a afastar-se de suas atividades profissionais, devido à punição ou ameaça de punição; direito à conclusão de curso interrompido por punição ou ao registro de diploma obtido em instituição de ensino fora do país; e direito à reintegração dos servidores públicos civis e dos empregados públicos. Como se pode notar, a Lei procurou trazer meios capazes de restabelecer as condições dos perseguidos políticos, tanto economicamente quanto simbolicamente12. Aliás, no campo da reparação 11 O resultado do trabalho da Comissão foi publicado no livro BRASIL. Secretaria Especial dos Direitos Humanos. Comissão Especial sobre Mortos e Desaparecidos Políticos. Direito à verdade e à memória. Brasília: Secretaria Especial dos Direitos Humanos, 2007. A publicação e o lançamento deste livro no ano de 2007, em uma grande solenidade ocorrida no Palácio do Planalto, com as presenças do Presidente da República, Luis Inácio Lula da Silva, o Ministro da Defesa, Nelson Jobim, a Ministra-Chefe da Casa Civil, Dilma Roussef e o Ministro da Secretaria Especial dos Direitos Humanos da Presidência da República, Paulo Vannuchi, representou um avanço significativo do Brasil no resgate da sua memória política. A obra, que demarca a conclusão dos trabalhos da Comissão Especial dobre Mortos e Desaparecidos Políticos pode ser consultada no seguinte endereço eletrônico: http://www.presidencia.gov.br/estrutura_presidencia/sedh/.arquivos/livrodireitomemoriaeverdadeid.pdf 12 Ampliando a reparação e evidenciando o cuidado e a preocupação com o olhar das vítimas da repressão ditatorial, a Comissão de Anistia lançou em março de 2013 o Projeto Clínicas do Testemunho, que pretende fornecer assistência psicológica aos que foram atingidos pela repressão política. O projeto contou em sua preparação com o auxílio de especialistas da área e prevê a sua execução em parceria com instituições aprovadas em Edital público com verba, apoio e estrutura para dar conta de prover essa assistência. O projeto prevê a sua execução primeiramente nas cidades de São Paulo, Porto Alegre, Recife e Rio de Janeiro, com a expectativa de ampliação para outras cidades em uma segunda fase. Para maiores informações ver: http://blog.justica.gov.br/inicio/tag/clinicas-do-testemunho/ (Acesso em 07/01/2014). Outro aspecto digno de nota é que a experiência das Clínicas do Testemunho poderá ser aproveitada para que se efetive um projeto semelhante para o tratamento de vítimas das atuais práticas criminosas de agentes públicos, especialmente, da tortura, ainda numerosa no país. simbólica, a partir de 2007, a Comissão da Anistia passou a formalmente, em cada caso de deferimento do pedido de reparação fomulado, pedir desculpas pelos erros cometidos pelo Estado. Tal pedido de desculpas traduz um ato de reconhecimento da legitimidade do direito de resistência dos opositores do regime militar. Cabe registrar ainda a importância que as Caravanas da Anistia assumiram nesse contexto, já que durante essas ocasiões – quando ocorrem julgamentos públicos de requerimentos feitos por perseguidos políticos em diferentes cidades e espaços comunitários do país – é dado espaço de fala para as vítimas. Durante esses momentos, aqueles que tiveram desrespeitados seus direitos fundamentais de livre expressão e consciência podem testemunhar e oferecer a sua versão dos acontecimentos – quebrando-se, assim, a lógica do silêncio das vítimas e da “verdade oficial”13. A opção do Brasil em priorizar a efetivação do direito à reparação acabou influenciando diretamente na dimensão da busca pela verdade. Isso porque o trabalho das comissões de reparação, em boa medida, promoveu um questionamento da versão dos fatos oferecida pelos órgãos do estado ditatorial. Para conceder indenização pecuniária, por exemplo, as comissões investigaram a circunstância da morte dos desaparecidos e das perseguições de milhares de perseguidos políticos, reconhecendo a participação do poder público e desqualificando versões esdrúxulas oficializadas pelo regime militar (como as mortes supostamente ocorridas por suicídio, conforme registro oficial, ou por mirabolantes e fantasiosos acidentes, como se registrou em inúmeras investigações policiais do período). As atenções atualmente voltam-se à Comissão Nacional da Verdade que busca estender e consolidar as conquistas obtidas até a sua Há ainda que se mencionar, no campo da reparação simbólica a iniciativa do Edital Marcas da Memória. Divulgado anualmente desde 2010 o Edital Marcas da Memória faz parte das políticas de memória executadas pela Comissão de Anistia e tem por objetivo destinar verba pública a projetos culturais, artísticos e científicos voltados ao resgate da memória política brasileira. Ver: BAGGIO, Roberta Camineiro. Marcas da Memória: a atuação da Comissão de Anistia no campo das políticas públicas de transição no Brasil. In: Ciências Sociais Unisinos, São Leopoldo, Vol. 48, N. 2, p. 111-118, mai/ago 2012. 13 Até agosto de 2013, 72 Caravanas foram realizadas em todo o Brasil. Em recente publicação, apoiada pelo Projeto Marcas da Memória, está o detalhamento das primeiras 50 Caravanas realizadas acompanhado de diversos textos escritos sobre o significado das Caravanas, escritos por diversas personalidades dentre artistas, intelectuais, pesquisadores, ex-perseguidos políticos, juristas, jornalistas, entre outros. Ver: COELHO, Maria José H.; ROTTA, Vera (orgs.). Caravanas da Anistia: o Brasil pede perdão. Brasília: Ministério da Justiça; Florianópolis: Comunicação, Estudos e Consultoria, 2012. Uma descrição mais sucinta de todas as Caravanas realizadas de 2007 a 2010 pode ser vista em: Ações Educativas da Comissão de Anistia - relatório de gestão 2007-2010. Brasília: Ministério da Justiça, 2010. Para as Caravanas mais recentes, inclusive com vídeos, entrevistas e transcrição de depoimentos, ver o Blog do Ministério da Justiça no site: http://blog.justica.gov.br instalação, em 2012 Em compensação, pouco tem-se progredido no que tange à reforma das instituições e à responsabilização dos agentes policiais e militares que violaram normas de direitos humanos. Em que pese as instituições (tais como o Serviço Nacional de Informações, as Divisões de Segurança Institucional, o Departamento de Operações de Informações - Centro de Operações de Defesa Interna e os Departamentos de Ordem Política e Social) responsáveis pela repressão organizada do regime de exceção terem sido extintas, o fato é que a cultura de desrespeito e desvalorização dos direitos humanos tem ganhado espaço perante as forças de segurança pública do país. Se é verdade que a reparação das vítimas está intimamente ligada ao direito à verdade, é preciso reconhecer a relação que a reforma das instituições possui com o campo da responsabilização14. Não é difícil de entender o porquê: os agentes estatais que estiveram envolvidos em crimes de lesa- humanidade, além de não terem sido responsabilizados, foram realocados nos quadros da administração pública e levam consigo os métodos utilizados na abordagem dos que outrora eram denominados de “subversivos”. A lógica do direito penal do inimigo assume uma nova veste (já que o inimigo muda de denominação), mas a sua essência – que é a negação da esfera de direitos do outro – segue intocável, assim como a forma de atacá-lo15. 14 Esta relação é apontada na pesquisa de Kathryn Sikkink. Ver: SIKKINK, Kathryn. The Justice Cascade - how human rights procesutions are changing world politics. New York, London: W.W. Norton & Company, 2011. Ver também o artigo: SIKKINK, Kathryn. WALLING, Carrie Booth. The impact of human rights trials in Latin America. Journal of Peace Research, Los Angeles, London, New Delhi, Singapore, vol.44, n.4, 2007, p.427-445. 15 Importa esclarecer que não se ignora ser a violência policial uma característica tradicional das forças de segurança pública brasileiras, desde antes do advento do golpe de Estado de 1964, desde as práticas escravistas até a era Vargas, contudo, a ditadura então instalada contribuiu significativamente não apenas para dar continuidade a esta macabra tradição como aprofundá-la dentro das corporações e das instituições brasileiras ligadas à segurança pública. Nesse sentido, ver o interessante estudo de Martha Huggins: HUGGINS, Martha Knisely; ZIMBARDO, Philip G.; HARITOS-FATOUROS, Mika. Operários da Violência – policiais torturadores e assassinos reconstroem as atrocidades brasileiras. Brasília: UnB, 2006. Ver também: JESUS, Maria Gorete Marques de. O crime de tortura e a justiça criminal: um estudo dos processos de tortura na cidade de São Paulo. São Paulo: IBCCRIM, 2010. (Monografias, 55). Corroborando o elevado índice de mortes e torturas praticadas pelas forças policiais brasileiras, ver os relatórios: NUCLEO DE ESTUDOS DE CIDADANIA, CONFLITO E VIOLÊNCIA (UFRJ). “Autos de" resistência: uma análise dos homicídios cometidos por policiais na cidade do Rio de Janeiro (2001-2011). Disponível em: http://www.necvu.ifcs.ufrj.br/images/Relatorio%20final%20Autos%20de%20Resist%C3%AAncia.pdf Acesso em: 07/01/2014; HUMAN RIGHTS WATCH. Lethal Force. Police Violence and Public Security in Rio de Janeiro and São Paulo. Disponível em: http://www.hrw.org/sites/default/files/reports/brazil1209webwcover.pdf . Acesso em 07/01/2014; JUSTIÇA GLOBAL. Segurança, Tráfico e Milícias no Rio de Janeiro. Disponível em: http://global.org.br/wp-content/uploads/2009/12/Relatorio_Milicias_completo.pdf . Acesso em A responsabilização é, das quatro dimensões da justiça de transição, a única que segue ainda estagnada. Como já foi exposto, a busca pela responsabilização dos agentes que utilizaram a estrutura do Estado para perseguir, torturar e assassinar sempre foi posta em pauta diante do Judiciário, mas tem esbarrado na anistia “ampla, geral e irrestrita” de 1979. Uma análise superficial poderia resultar na conclusão de que a Lei de Anistia é um empecilho, um “erro” no percurso das transições políticas. Ocorre que, a anistia de 1979 trouxe a estabilidade política necessária para que os militares se sentissem seguros o suficiente para, se não auxiliar, ao menos não dificultar o processo de abertura política. Assim, é preciso reconhecer o papel de destaque que o instituto da anistia desempenhou para que a democracia ganhasse espaço diante do aparelho autoritário de poder. A função desse mecanismo, contudo, não pode ser impossibilitar eternamente a responsabilização. O prejuízo que haveria para a sociedade brasileira se houvesse julgamentos tão logo o regime de exceção tivesse se encerrado equipara-se ao dano causado pelo bloqueio perene das vias de responsabilização defendido atualmente. Estudos na área da justiça transicional concluem que “a responsabilização (julgamento) deve ser equilibrada com a estabilidade (anistia) para obter êxito”16. Explicando a relação responsabilização-estabilidade, os pesquisadores referem que “em alguns casos, anistias fornecem a estabilidade que mais tarde permite que democracias fortes processem os perpetradores e estabeleçam a proteção dos direitos humanos. (…) Nesse cenário, o equilíbrio envolve dar sequência à responsabilização após a anistia ter favorecido a estabilidade política”17. Foi justamente por compartilhar dessa compreensão que o Ministério da Justiça, em 2008, organizou a audiência pública “Limites e possibilidades para a responsabilização jurídica dos agentes violadores de 07/01/2014; JUSTIÇA GLOBAL. Execuções Sumárias, Arbitrárias e Extrajudiciais. Uma aproximação da realidade brasileira. Disponível em: http://dhnet.org.br/dados/relatorios/r_jglobal/r_jg_exec_extra_judiciais1.pdf. Acesso em 07/01/2014; AMNISTIA INTERNACIONAL BRASIL. “Entrán Disparando”: La actuación policial em las comunidades socialmente excluidas. Disponível em: http://www.amnesty.org/es/library/asset/AMR19/025/2005/es/d6c16d41-d49c-11dd-8a23- d58a49c0d652/amr190252005pt.html. Acesso em 07/01/2014. 16 OLSEN, Tricia D.; PAYNE, Leigh; REITER, Andrew G. As implicações políticas dos processos de anistia. In: ABRÃO, Paulo; PAYNE, Leigh; TORELLY, Marcelo. A Anistia na Era da Responsabilização: o Brasil em perspectiva internacional e comparada. Brasília: Ministério da Justiça, 2010p.563. Ver também dos mesmo autores: OLSEN, Tricia D.; PAYNE, Leigh; REITER, Andrew G. Transitional Justice in Balance - comparing processes, weighing efficacy. Washington, D.C.: United States Institute of Peace Press, 2010. 17 Ibidem, p.564. direitos humanos durante o estado de exceção no Brasil”. O tabu da anistia bilateral estava prestes a ser enfrentado, pela primeira vez, diante de um Estado democraticamente constituído e organizado. Foram as ideias veiculadas durante essa audiência pública, que contou com a participação da sociedade civil e de agentes políticos do poder legislativo, do poder executivo e do Ministério Público, que embasaram a pretensão do Conselho Federal da Ordem dos Advogados do Brasil de questionar, perante o Supremo Tribunal Federal via Arguição de Descumprimento de Preceito Fundamental, a interpretação da Lei de Anistia de 1979. Também podem ser identificados como fatores que contribuíram para a iniciativa do Conselho Federal da OAB as reviravoltas ocorridas nos países do Cone Sul onde foram reconhecidos como nulos os indultos oferecidos pelos regimes ditatoriais, passando-se para promoção de julgamentos e punições dos agentes estatais. Cabe destacar as três principais teses de fundamentação que, na provocação do Poder Judiciário, poderiam ser defendidas para questionar a extensão da anistia: a primeira, de que a Lei Nº 6.683/1979 não poderia representar um empecilho à responsabilização dos agentes do Estado porque isso seria contrariar a jurisprudência da Corte Interamericana de Direitos Humanos que considera como nulo o instituto da auto- anistia; a segunda, de que os crimes cometidos pelo Estado, por meio de seus agentes, não podem ser entendidos como “conexos” aos crimes políticos de modo que, embora essa tenha sido a intenção do governo militar, a anistia não incidia sobre eles; e por fim, a terceira, de que embora seja possível válida a anistia bilateral, é inadmissível aplicá-la a crimes permanentes (sequestro e ocultação de cadáver, por exemplo) e aos que ocorreram depois de 1979. Tanto a primeira quanto a segunda tese de fundamentação foram sustentadas na petição inicial da ADPF Nº 15318. No entanto, durante o julgamento, o STF afastou esses argumentos adotando a seguinte postura: quanto ao primeiro posicionou-se no sentido de qualificar como legítima a anistia de 1979, com base no fato de ela ter sido resultado do trabalho do Congresso Nacional e consequentemente não se enquadrar no perfil de uma auto-anistia; e quanto ao segundo, compreendeu que, embora os crimes dos agentes do Estado não se enquadrem no 18 BRASIL. Supremo Tribunal Federal. Ação de Descumprimento de Preceito Fundamental Nº 153/DF. Arguente: Conselho Federal da Ordem dos Advogados do Brasil. Arguidos: Presidente da República e Congresso Nacional. Relator Ministro Luis Fux. Brasília/DF: 29 de abril de 2010. Disponível em:. Acesso em 25 ago. 2013. conceito de crimes políticos, a “conexão” criada pela Lei Nº 6.683 é sui generis (não se trata da conexão conhecida no processo penal) e representa o expoente do acordo bilateral firmado entre governo militar e oposição. A terceira tese surgiu nos embargos de declaração interpostos pelo Conselho Federal da OAB contra a decisão do Supremo na ADPF Nº 153, que, no momento da redação deste artigo, ainda aguardava julgamento. A decisão do STF na ADPF Nº 153 assume a importância de ser o precedente jurisprudencial da Suprema Corte brasileira que mais diretamente se debruçou sobre o tema da transição política pátria no aspecto da responsabilização. Nesse julgamento, os Ministros do STF puderam manifestar o seu entendimento a respeito da validade e do alcance da Lei de anistia de 1979. Com base no que ficou registrado na ADPF Nº 153 serão confrontadas algumas premissas assumidas em sede de outras decisões proferidas por esse mesmo órgão jurisdicional, quais sejam: a ADPF Nº 130, a Extradição Nº 974, a Extradição Nº 1.150 e a Extradição Nº 1.278. O Partido Democrático Trabalhista - PDT ajuizou a ADPF Nº 13019 questionando a recepção da Lei Nº 5.250/1967 (conhecida como Lei de Imprensa) pela ordem constitucional estabelecida em 1988. Conforme o defendido na petição inicial, a norma atacada era incompatível com os tempos democráticos por restringir a liberdade de expressão e cercear a liberdade de imprensa. No dia 30 de Abril de 2009 o STF, por maioria, reconheceu a procedência da ação para negar a recepção da Lei de Imprensa – aprovada pelo Congresso Nacional e promulgada durante o regime militar – pela Constituição Cidadã. A EXT Nº 97420 envolveu o pedido de extradição formulado pelo governo argentino em relação ao cidadão uruguaio Manuel Cordeiro Piacentini. O major do exército uruguaio foi acusado de participar de crimes de associação ilícita voltada à prática de crimes durante a Operação Condor nos países do Cone Sul. No dia 6 de 19 BRASIL. Supremo Tribunal Federal. Ação de Descumprimento de Preceito Fundamental Nº 130/DF. Arguente: Partido Democrático Trabalhista. Arguidos: Presidente da República, Congresso Nacional, Federação Nacional dos Jornalistas Profissionais, Associação Brasileira de Imprensa e Artigo 19 Brasil. Relator Ministro Carlos Ayres Britto. Brasília/DF: 30 de abril de 2009. Disponível em: . Acesso em 25 ago. 2013. 20 BRASIL. Supremo Tribunal Federal. Extradição Nº 974. Requerente: Governo da República Argentina. Extraditando: Manoel Cordeiro Piacentini. Relator Ministro Marco Aurélio Mello; Relator p/ acórdão Ministro Ricardo Lewandowski. Brasília/DF: 06 de agosto de 2009. Disponível em . Acesso em 25 ago. 2013. Agosto de 2009 o STF, por maioria, deferiu o pedido de extradição, reconhecendo a possibilidade do uruguaio ser punido pelos crimes cometidos durante o regime de exceção. De igual modo, o governo da Argentina requisitou a extradição dos cidadãos argentinos Norberto Raul Tozzo (EXT Nº 1.15021) e Cláudio Vallejos (EXT Nº 1.27822) pela prática de crimes de desaparecimentos forçados durante o regime militar argentino. O resultado desses dois julgamentos seguiram o decidido no precedente da EXT Nº 974, e o STF atendeu ao pedido de extradição dos dois nacionais argentinos para que houvesse a devida persecução criminal. 4. A Suprema Corte brasileira enfrentando a responsabilização Inicialmente, revela-se importante a constatação de que as premissas assumidas pelos Ministros do STF nos julgamentos da ADPF Nº 130 e da ADPF Nº 153 são diametralmente opostas. Quando analisaram a primeira, precisamente um ano antes da segunda, os Ministros reconheceram o conteúdo autoritário da Lei de Imprensa que tinha o objetivo principal de impedir a difusão de ideias e críticas que pudessem levar à mobilização social em face do regime vigente à época. Por conta disso, entendendo que o conteúdo dessa lei contraria frontalmente os valores que foram elevados à hierarquia de norma constitucional, o STF fez prevalecer a Constituição de 1988 e fulminou o ato normativo autoritário atacado. Nesse caso, o Egrégio Tribunal assumiu o papel de defensor da Constituição, afastando do ordenamento jurídico uma norma que, embora promulgada pelo parlamento em 1967, carregava um sentido autoritário. Postura adversa foi adotada durante a análise da ADPF Nº 153. Na ocasião do julgamento que discutia a interpretação da Lei de Anistia de 1979, o STF descumpriu a sua missão constitucional de fortalecer e tornar efetivas as disposições da Carta Magna. Houve inclusive a sustentação de que o Poder Judiciário não está autorizado a alterar o texto normativo ou a dar outra redação, diversa da nele contemplada. A explicação para 21BRASIL. Supremo Tribunal Federal. Extradição Nº 1150. Requerente: Governo da República Argentina. Extraditando: Norberto Raul Tozzo. Relatora Ministra Carmem Lúcia. Brasília/DF: 19 de maio de 2011. Disponível em . Acesso em 25 ago. 2013. 22 BRASIL. Supremo Tribunal Federal. Extradição Nº 1278. Requerente: Governo da República Argentina. Extraditando: Claudio Vallejos. Relator Ministro Gilmar Mendes. Brasília/DF: 18 de setembro de 2012. Disponível em . Acesso em 25 ago. 2013. essa fundamentação foi a classificação das leis de anistia como “leis medida”. Segundo o Ministro Eros Grau, defensor desse posicionamento, a anistia de 1979 veicula uma decisão política assumida naquele momento, não podendo ser entendida como uma “regra para o futuro”23. Uma segunda constatação, a partir do estudo dos acórdãos selecionados, é a contradição existente no âmbito da Suprema Corte a respeito da prescrição dos crimes dos agentes estatais que violaram normas de direitos humanos. É importante não esquecer que a anistia e a prescrição são causas de extinção da punibilidade que não se confundem. Para que haja, portanto, a possibilidade de persecução criminal desses crimes é necessário afastar tanto a incidência da anistia, quanto a incidência da prescrição. Em outras palavras, o afastamento de um instituto não implicará o do outro. Foi por isso, inclusive, que alguns Ministros do STF desqualificaram a discussão a 23 No seu voto, que foi acompanhado pela maioria dos demais Ministros, Eros Grau registrou que: "A Lei n. 6.683 é uma lei-medida, não uma regra para o futuro, dotada de abstração e generalidade. Há de ser interpretada a partir da realidade no momento em que foi conquistada. (...) A Constituição não recebe, certamente, leis em sentido material, abstratas e gerais, mas não afeta, também certamente, leis-medida que a tenham precedido". (BRASIL. Supremo Tribunal Federal. Ação de Descumprimento de Preceito Fundamental Nº 153/DF. Arguente: Conselho Federal da Ordem dos Advogados do Brasil. Arguidos: Presidente da República e Congresso Nacional. Relator Ministro Luis Fux. Brasília/DF: 29 de abril de 2010. Disponível em: . Acesso em 25 ago. 2013). Como anota em sua obra Emilio Peluso Neder Meyer, o coneito de "lei- medida" foi importado de Erns Fortshoff, que o produziu no contexto da Alemanha pós-Primeira Guerra Mundial, querendo com ele indicar a necessidade da edição de leis com caráter administativo e concreto, ou seja, despidas das características normalmente associadas às "leis-norma", quais sejam a generalidade e a abstração. Conforme salienta Meyer a invocação do conceito pelo Relator Eros Grau é inadequada por três razões: 1) por pretender dar um tratamento não normativo à violação de direitos fundamentais causada pela anistia aos agentes da ditadura que praticaram crimes de lesa-humanidade (afetando neste caso os direitos das vítimas), o que quer dizer que mesmo que a categoria lei-medida pudesse se manter de pé, ela certamente não poderia ser aplicada a uma lei de anistia; 2) pelo fato de que mesmo que se pudesse admitir como correta a existência de uma "lei-medida" ela não poderia ficar à margem do controle de constitucionalidade das leis em geral (o que ficou consignado na própria jurisprudência do STF na MC-ADI Nº 4.048-1/DF, julgada em 14 de maio de 2008, em voto majoritário do Ministro Gilmar Mendes e que foi, inclusive, seguido pelo Ministro Eros Grau); 3) por restar superado pelos avanços teóricos no campo da hermenêutica e da filosofia da linguagem, especialmente quando busca contrapor uma esfera concreta a outra abstrata da norma. A própria noção gadameriana de applicatio, invocada constantemente pelo Ministro Eros Grau para fundamentar a sua afirmação de que a norma só existe quando interpretada e de que não se deve separar o momento da interpretação do momento da aplicação, já é suficiente para mostrar o desacerto do conceito de "lei-medida", como também serve para evidenciar o contra-senso argumentativo do Ministro em voltar-se contra suas próprias teses ao recomendar que uma lei seja interpretada não com os olhos do presente mas com os olhos da época, como se fosse possível abstrair do que se sabe hoje e contemplar os fatos como se estivéssemos postados em um momento e local já ultrapassados por nossas próprias experiências. Ver: MEYER, Emilio Peluso Neder. Ditadura e Responsabilização - elementos para uma justiça de transição no Brasil. Belo Horizonte: Arraes, 2012. p.68-75; e também: SILVA FILHO, José Carlos Moreira da . O Julgamento da ADPF 153 pelo Supremo Tribunal Federal e a Inacabada Transição Democrática Brasileira. In: Wilson Ramos Filho. (Org.). Trabalho e Regulação - as lutas sociais e as condições materiais da democracia. Belo Horizonte- MG: Fórum, 2012, v. 1, p. 129-177. respeito do alcance da anistia, sustentando a inequívoca incidência da prescrição. O Ministro Marco Aurélio fez constar em seu voto que a discussão trazida pela ADPF Nº 153 era estritamente acadêmica e serviria apenas para ficar nos Anais do Tribunal. Na análise dos julgamentos das extradições, é possível perceber que o STF manifestou-se no sentido de reconhecer a não incidência da prescrição nos crimes de sequestro (desaparecimento forçado) praticados pelos estrangeiros Manuel Cordeiro Piacentini, Norberto Raul Tozzo e Cláudio Vallejos. Nesses casos, como não estava ainda previsto na legislação penal brasileira o crime de desaparecimento forçado, o STF entendeu que a conduta criminosa imputada aos extraditandos era análoga à figura do sequestro, esta sim já prevista na legislação brasileira, e que, portanto, como até os dias presentes não se revelou o paradeiro das vítimas, o crime é permanente, não tendo havido ainda o início da contagem do prazo prescricional. O precedente deu embasamento aos Embargos Declaratórios interpostos contra a decisão proferida na ADPF Nº 15324, já que raciocínio semelhante foi adotado pela própria Corte Interamericana de Direitos Humanos na condenação do Brasil no Caso Gomes Lund, na qual aceitou-se a ingerência da Corte sobre a responsabilidade dos crimes praticados pelos agentes da ditadura na Guerrilha do Araguaia, visto que embora a jurisdição da Corte só tenha sido aceita pelo Brasil em 1992, quase 20 anos após a Guerrilha do Araguaia, ela incide sobre crimes que embora iniciados no passado ainda continuam sendo praticados após a data da adesão, ou seja, são crimes permanentes25. A tese levantada nos Embargos Declaratórios é a de que sobre crimes permanentes 24 No momento da redação deste artigo, os Embargos Declaratórios seguem pendentes de apreciação. De todo modo, é interessante identificar a breve manifestação na EXT Nº 1150, cujo julgamento ocorreu após o da ADPF Nº 153, do novo Relator, Ministro Luis Fux, que substituiu o Ministro Eros Grau após a sua aposentadoria. Está ela a indicar alguma possível reviravolta na decisão do STF diante da ADPF Nº 153? Só o futuro dirá. Disse o Ministro Luis Fux no início do seu voto: "(...) esse é um momento importante para a minha geração, porque esse Massacre de Margarita Belén foi exatamente um evento político que marcou muito a minha juventude, assim como também a bomba do Riocentro e todos esses eventos que se encaixam bem na advertência de um poeta latino de que 'Quando não lembramos o que nos aconteceu, pode vir a acontecer tudo outra vez'" (BRASIL. Supremo Tribunal Federal. Extradição Nº 1150. Requerente: Governo da República Argentina. Extraditando: Norberto Raul Tozzo. Relatora Ministra Carmem Lúcia. Brasília/DF: 19 de maio de 2011. Disponível em . Acesso em 25 ago. 2013). O ex-major argentino Norberto Raul Tozzo, o extraditando em questão, foi acusado na Argentina de ter comandado o conhecido Massacre de Margarita Belén, no qual 22 jovens peronistas foram torturados e fuzilados. 25 Essa também tem sido a tese adotada pelo Ministério Público Federal após a condenação do Brasil pela Corte Interamericana de Direitos Humanos, o que tem rendido um conjunto de acões interpostas pelo MPF que visam a responsabilização de agentes da ditadura responsáveis por desaparecimentos forçados, tais como Sebastião Curió, Carlos Alberto Brilhatne Ustra, Dirceu Gravina, Lício Maciel, entre outros. não incide a prescrição, logo, haveria possibilidade de haver julgamentos no Brasil pelos sequestros e ocultações de cadáveres cometidos pelos agentes militares. Ocorre que o afastamento da prescrição, como também já foi apontado, não é o suficiente: é preciso afastar a anistia. Aliás, nos julgamentos das extradições referidas no presente estudo, o STF só reconheceu a não incidência da prescrição nos crimes de caráter permanente depois de considerar o afastamento dos indultos dos quais tinham se beneficiado os extraditandos. Assim, revela-se imprescindível – no caso brasileiro – afastar a incidência da anistia de 1979. O argumento que tem recebido acolhida por grande parte dos que lutam pela responsabilização dos agentes que cometeram crimes de lesa-humanidade durante o regime militar é o de que o caráter permanente de alguns crimes inviabilizaria a sua anistia. Concretamente, observando a realidade brasileira, essa construção pretende questionar a possibilidade de uma lei de anistia (que traz determinado um período certo de tempo dentro do qual ocorreram as condutas criminosas anistiadas) atingir crimes de caráter permanente, que continuam acontecendo – já que sua consumação se prolonga no tempo – até os dias de hoje. Diante dos argumentos utilizados pelo STF para negar o pedido constante da ADPF 153, é possível que a tese dos crimes permanentes não seja acolhida26. Por fim, vale apontar a inverossimilhança de três teses veiculadas pelos Ministros do STF no julgamento da ADPF 153. Em primeiro lugar, destaque-se a sustentação do Ministro Cezar Peluso de que não houve tentativas de responsabilização dos agentes da ditadura. Procurou-se mostrar no início desse trabalho que nas ocasiões em que o Estado brasileiro, via provocação do Poder Judiciário, foi chamado a promover a responsabilização desses crimes, a anistia de 1979 representou um obstáculo intransponível. Aliás, como foi possível constatar, a Lei de Anistia inviabilizou inclusive a persecução de crimes cometidos após 1979. Não faltou oportunidade para que o Poder Judiciário promovesse a punição dos crimes de lesa-humanidade, faltaram órgãos jurisdicionais suficientemente comprometidos nesses casos com os valores da Constituição de 1988 e o com os compromissos assumidos perante o Direito 26 Ainda que possa parecer estranho considerar anistiado um crime que continua a ocorrer, o que seria uma hipótese curiosa de anistia para o futuro, é possível que o STF adote a tese de que como a anistia teria excluído a ilicitude do ato inicial, não caberia arguir a ilicitude da sua continuidade, daí a importância em realmente se afastar a incidência da lei de anistia para os crimes de lesa-humanidade, em geral, praticados pelos agentes ditatoriais. Internacional, aos quais o país está legalmente submetido. Um outro ponto que merece atenção é a convalidação, pelo STF, de um suposto acordo bilateral que teria sido firmado entre o regime autoritário e a sua oposição. Nos termos desse acordo, aqueles que golpearam a Constituição de 1946 e tomaram o poder pela força permitiriam que os civis reassumissem o governo desde que os crimes cometidos pelos primeiros (crimes de lesa-humanidade) fossem perdoados. A declaração da Ministra Ellen Gracie em seu voto na ADPF Nº 153 não deixa dúvidas: Não se faz transição, ao menos não se faz transição pacífica, entre um regime autoritário e uma democracia plena, sem concessões recíprocas. Por incômodo que seja reconhecê-lo hoje, quando vivemos outro e mais virtuoso momento histórico, a anistia inclusive daqueles que cometeram crimes nos porões da ditadura, foi o preço que a sociedade brasileira pagou para acelerar o processo pacífico de redemocratização(...)” 27. Assim, o STF confirmou a legitimidade da pretensão dos que vislumbraram uma troca: entrega-se a democracia desde que se desconsidere alguns direitos fundamentais. Para além desse questionamento envolvendo a matéria desse acordo – que, data venia, é inaceitável – é preciso lembrar a disparidade de forças existente durante o regime de exceção, que inviabiliza a compreensão de que houve um “acordo”. O pressuposto básico de um acordo – que é a existência de partes minimamente equiparadas - não existiu28. A análise dos acórdãos selecionados neste estudo revela de um lado uma flagrante contradição na jurisprudência da própria Corte, ora realizando o controle de adequação de leis autoritárias anteriores diante da Constituição, como o fez no julgamento da ADPF Nº 130, ora fazendo prevalecer a legislação autoritária anterior, como ocorreu no julgamento da ADPF Nº 153. Este último julgamento, por sua vez, denota uma continuidade no que se refere ao lastro autoritário deixado pelo golpe militar de 1964. 27 BRASIL. Supremo Tribunal Federal. Ação de Descumprimento de Preceito Fundamental Nº 153/DF. Arguente: Conselho Federal da Ordem dos Advogados do Brasil. Arguidos: Presidente da República e Congresso Nacional. Relator Ministro Luis Fux. Brasília/DF: 29 de abril de 2010. Disponível em: . Acesso em 25 ago. 2013. 28 Explorando mais amiúde os motivos para a inexistência do alegado acordo, ver: SILVA FILHO, José Carlos Moreira da . O Julgamento da ADPF 153 pelo Supremo Tribunal Federal e a Inacabada Transição Democrática Brasileira. In: Wilson Ramos Filho. (Org.). Trabalho e Regulação - as lutas sociais e as condições materiais da democracia. Belo Horizonte-MG: Fórum, 2012, v. 1, p. 129-177. Se a Constituição de 1988 representou uma ruptura de paradigmas no que diz respeito a muitos assuntos tratados pelos constituintes, o mesmo impacto não ocorreu em matéria de justiça de transição – sobretudo no que se refere ao campo da responsabilização. Para chegar a essa conclusão basta identificar que houve o acolhimento do argumento, por alguns Ministros, de que a Emenda Constitucional Nº 26 de 1985 selava a anistia bilateral, sem que a Constituição de 1988 pudesse romper com ela. O entendimento, portanto, foi de que o Poder Constituinte Originário que deu origem à Constituição de 1988 estava limitado por normas pré-constitucionais, como se verá com mais detalhes no próximo item. 5. O STF e a vinculação do Brasil à Convenção Americana de Direitos Humanos Há outro aspecto crucial no qual o STF demonstra flagrante contradição quando se compara a decisão tomada na ADPF Nº 153 com decisões anteriores que tomou. Tal aspecto é o que sinaliza para a vinculação do Brasil ao Pacto de San Jose da Costa Rica e a sua submissão à jurisdição da Corte Interamericana de Direitos Humanos. Em 25 de setembro de 1992 o Brasil depositou sua carta de adesão à Convenção Americana de Direitos Humanos (Pacto de San José da Costa Rica). Posteriormente, em 10 de dezembro de 1998 o Brasil reconheceu a competência da Corte Interamericana de Direitos Humanos, a ela se submetendo soberanamente. Este fato gerou uma discussão acerca da estatura hierárquica das normas garantidoras de direitos humanos presentes na Convenção mas não explicitadas no texto constitucional. De 05 de outubro de 1988 até a Emenda Constitucional Nº 45, promulgada em 30 de dezembro de 2004, o Art. 5º da Constituição de 1988 trazia apenas dois parágrafos após a enumeração dos incisos definidores de direitos e garantias fundamentais. O § 1º estabeleceu a aplicabilidade imediata e o § 2º estabeleceu o princípio da abertura do catálogo de direitos fundamentais demarcando que os "direitos e garantias expressos nesta Constituição não excluem outros decorrentes do regime e dos princípios por ela adotados, ou dos tratados internacionais em que a República Federativa do Brasil seja parte". A presença solitária desses parágrafos, ainda sem o acréscimo do 3º e 4º 29, que viriam somente com a EC Nº45, criou a dúvida a respeito da 29 O parágrafo 3º do Art. 5º, criado pela EC Nº 45/2004, estabelece que "os tratados e convenções internacionais sobre direitos humanos que forem aprovados, em cada casa do Congresso Nacional, em estatura hierárquica dos direitos e garantias expressos nos tratados internacionais de direitos humanos aos quais o Brasil havia aderido após a promulgação da Constituição, isto porque até então a jurisprudência consolidada do STF era de que os tratados de direitos humanos teriam o status de lei ordinária. Foi em 03 de dezembro de 2008, com a decisão do leading case que discutiu a prisão civil do depositário infiel (HC 87.585/TO30 e RE 466.343/SP) que o posicionamento do STF atingiu um novo patamar sobre o tema do status dos tratados de direitos humanos. A Constituição de 1988 previu em seu Art.5º, LXVII que "não haverá prisão civil por dívida, salvo a do responsável pelo inadimplemento voluntário e inescusável de obrigação alimentícia e a do depositário infiel". Por outro lado, a Convenção Americana de Direitos Humanos estabeleceu em seu Art. 7º que "ninguém deve ser detido por dívidas", excepcionando apenas o caso do devedor alimentar. A solução encontrada pelo STF para dirimir a antinomia clara entre a Convenção e a própria Constituição brasileira tanto nos casos citados acima como em outros que se seguiram31 foi estabelecer duas importantes inovações. A primeira delas significou a mudança da jurisprudência que delimitava a estatura de mera lei ordinária aos tratados de direitos humanos. Vingou na opinião majoritária de 5 Ministros a tese da supralegalidade dos tratados de direitos humanos, isto é, são superiores às leis ordinárias mas inferiores à Constituição, ainda que façam parte de um bloco de constitucionalidade por especificarem direitos fundamentais referidos no texto constitucional. Registre-se que os outros 4 votos demarcavam a teoria do status constitucional dos tratados internacionais de direitos humanos, mesmo no caso de dois turnos, por três quintos dos votos dos respectivos membros, serão equivalentes às emendas constitucionais". Com isto, firmou-se o entendimento de que para um direito ou garantia expresso em um tratado ou convenção internacional de direitos humanos, firmado pelo país após a entrada em vigor da EC Nº 45, possa gozar do status constitucional ele deve passar pelo mesmo processo legislativo pelo qual passa uma Emenda Constitucional. Já o parágrafo 4º estabelece que "o Brasil se submete à jurisdição de Tribunal Penal Internacional a cuja criação tenha manifestado adesão". 30 BRASIL. Supremo Tribunal Federal. Habeas Corpus Nº 87.585/TO. Paciente: Alberto de Ribamar Ramos Costa. Coator: Superior Tribunal de Justiça. Relator Ministro Marco Aurélio Mello. Brasília/DF: 03 de dezembro de 2008. Disponível em: . Acesso em 25 ago. 2013; BRASIL. Supremo Tribunal Federal. Habeas Corpus Nº 466.343/SP. Recorrente: Banco Bradesco S/A. Recorrido: Luciano Cardoso Santos. Relator Ministro Cézar Peluso. Brasília/DF: 03 de dezembro de 2008. Disponível em: . Acesso em 25 ago. 2013. 31 O posicionamento adotado acabou por gerar a Súmula 25, a qual prevê que "é ilícita a prisão civil do depositário infiel, qualquer que seja a modalidade de depósito". tratados incorporados antes da EC Nº 45 e, portanto, sem a utilização do rito que passou a ser previsto no Art. 5º, §3º. Muito embora sejam mais aceitáveis sob o ponto de vista da coerência na busca de uma ordem jurídica cada vez mais forte na promoção e proteção dos direitos humanos tanto a tese do status constitucional quanto a da supraconstitucionalidade (os tratados de direitos humanos valem mais do que a própria Constituição), o STF optou pela via da supralegalidade. Ao menos avançou em relação à jurisprudência anterior. De todo modo, a adoção da supralegalidade dos tratados de direitos humanos não impediu no caso da prisão do depositário infiel que se desse preferência à Convenção Americana de Direitos Humanos em relação à Constituição brasileira. E esta é a segunda inovação. O fundamento adotado para tanto foi o princípio da aplicação da norma mais favorável em direitos humanos, ainda que em um engenho de argumentação se tenha estabelecido que tal predomínio não necessariamente revoga a norma constitucional restritiva mas impede que norma infraconstitucional lhe dê eficácia. Desse modo, ao mesmo tempo em que o STF afirmou que a Constituição vale mais que o tratado, assegurou que o tratado valesse mais do que qualquer lei ordinária e que no caso de norma mais favorável impedisse a regulamentação de dispositivo constitucional restritivo, prevalecendo inclusive sobre norma constitucional originária. Tal posicionamento causa espécie quando se vislumbra a decisão do STF sobre o status da lei de anistia de 1979. A suprema corte brasileira, embora não o declare explicitamente na decisão da ADPF Nº 153, conferiu prevalência à Lei Nº 6683/1979, especialmente em seu Art.1º, §1º, dispositivo que trata dos "crimes conexos" e que em interpretação predominante até aqui anistia agentes da ditadura que praticaram crimes de lesa humanidade, tanto sobre a Constituição de 1988 como sobre a Convenção Americana e a jurisprudência da Corte Interamericana sobre ela. E corre o risco de fazê- lo também em relação à decisão tomada pela Corte Interamericana de Direitos Humanos no Caso Gomes Lund, a depender da apreciação dos Embargos Declaratórios interpostos pela OAB na ADPF Nº 153, e que até a redação deste artigo seguiam pendentes de decisão. Tratando primeiramente da Constituição republicana de 1988, deve ser repudiada qualquer tentativa de vincular a soberania da constituinte a uma norma construída na ordem jurídica anterior, de perfil autoritário e ditatorial, mesmo que tenha sido uma norma que serviu para iniciar o processo constituinte como o foi a EC Nº 26/1985. Além da Lei Nº 6683/1979, a referida Emenda, em seu Art.4, §1º, também estabeleceu a anistia aos crimes conexos32. É preciso ter claro, contudo, que esta última norma emendou a Constituição anterior, a de 1969, instituída de modo autoritário em plena ditadura, pertencendo portanto à ordem jurídica instaurada de modo ilegítimo pelo golpe de 1964. Ao contrário do que defenderam o Ministro Eros Grau e o Ministro Gilmar Mendes em seus respectivos votos na ADPF 153, quaisquer condições impostas pela ordem constitucional anterior não podem ser tomadas como efetivas e limitadoras do poder constituinte originário, especialmente quando essa ordem anterior é autoritária. Assim, as disposições sobre anistia que constam na EC Nº 26/1985, bem como as que estão na Lei Nº 6683/79 só devem vincular a nova ordem naquilo que não sejam com ela incompatíveis. Ao contrário, a Constituição de 1988 deixou bem claros os seus pressupostos axiológicos e principiológicos quanto ao tema. Em seu Art.1º, III estabelece a dignidade da pessoa humana como fundamento da República; em seu Art. 4º, II estabelece que a República rege-se nas suas relações internacionais pelo princípio da prevalência dos direitos humanos; em seu Art.5º, XLIII prevê que a tortura é crime inafiançável e insuscetível de graça ou anistia33; e, finalmente, no Ato das Disposições Constitucionais Transitórias em seu Art. 8º menciona que "é concedida anistia aos que, no período de 18 de setembro de 1946 até a data da promulgação da Constituição, foram atingidos, em decorrência de motivação exclusivamente política, por atos de exceção, institucionais ou complementares", ou seja, nenhuma palavra em toda a longa extensão do texto constitucional sobre anistia a crimes conexos ou de qualquer natureza. Veja-se que quando se fala em anistia na Constituição de 1988 ela é direcionada para os que foram perseguidos políticos e não para os que realizaram esta perseguição, sem falar 32 Importante salientar que na EC Nº 26/1985 não foi reproduzida a enigmática definição do que seriam crimes conexos e que consta no Art.1º, §1º da Lei Nº 6683/1979, a saber: "Consideram-se conexos, para efeito deste artigo, os crimes de qualquer natureza relacionados com crimes políticos ou praticados por motivação política". 33 É verdade que o crime de terrorismo também é mencionado no mesmo dispositivo, mas antes que alguma análise mais apressada sugira que os participantes da luta armada contra a ditadura possam ser aí enquadrados, é preciso reconhecer dois fatos: que não há até os dias atuais qualquer tipificação do crime de terrorismo, seja na ordem jurídica interna, seja na ordem internacional, e que aqueles que pegaram em armas contra a ditadura não praticaram terrorismo mas sim exerceram o seu legítimo direito de resistência, colocado em prática exatamente para combater o terrorismo de Estado (sobre isto ver: SILVA FILHO, José Carlos Moreira da. O terrorismo de Estado e a ditadura civil-militar no Brasil: direito de resistência não é terrorismo. Revista Anistia Política e Justiça de Transição, Ministério da Justiça, n.5, jan/jul 2011, Brasília, p.50-74). que é explicitamente vedada no caso de crimes de tortura. É verdade que esta última previsão se volta aos casos posteriores a 1988, mas indica de todo modo o repúdio da nova ordem a atos de anistia voltados para este tipo de crime. Quanto à prevalência dos direitos humanos na ordem internacional, prevista no Art.4º, II da Constituição, depreende-se daí que a orientação a ser tomada deveria ser a mesma adotada no caso da vedação da prisão do depositário infiel, ou seja a de que os tratados de direitos humanos prevaleçam sobre qualquer norma da ordem jurídica interna que restrinjam os direitos e garantias ali previstos, ainda mais quando a norma colidente seja uma lei ordinária editada na ordem constitucional anterior. Em trecho didático da sentença prolatada pela Corte Internacional de Direitos Humanos no Caso Gomes Lund, que condenou o Brasil em relação aos crimes praticados pela ditadura durante a Guerrilha do Araguaia34 apresentam-se as violações dos artigos da Convenção que restam existentes enquanto a lei de anistia representar um obstáculo para a apuração e a responsabilização desses crimes: 172. A Corte Interamericana considera que a forma na qual foi interpretada e aplicada a Lei de Anistia aprovada pelo Brasil (...) afetou o dever internacional do Estado de investigar e punir as graves violações de direitos humanos, ao impedir que os familiares das vítimas no presente caso fossem ouvidos por um juiz, conforme estabelece o artigo 8.1 da Convenção Americana, e violou o direito à proteção judicial consagrado no artigo 25 do mesmo instrumento, precisamente pela falta de investigação, persecução, captura, julgamento e punição dos responsáveis pelos fatos, descumprindo também o artigo 1.1 da Convenção. Adicionalmente, ao aplicar a Lei de Anistia impedindo a investigação dos fatos e a identificação, julgamento e eventual sanção dos possíveis responsáveis por violações continuadas e permanentes, como os desaparecimentos forçados, o Estado descumpriu sua obrigação de adequar seu direito interno, consagrada no artigo 2 da Convenção Americana. 173. A Corte considera necessário enfatizar que, à luz das obrigações gerais consagradas nos artigos 1.1 e 2 da Convenção Americana, os Estados Parte têm o dever de adotar as providências de toda índole, para que ninguém seja privado da proteção judicial e do exercício do direito a um recurso simples e eficaz, nos termos dos artigos 8 e 25 da Convenção. Em um caso como o presente, uma vez ratificada a Convenção Americana, corresponde ao Estado, em conformidade com 34A audiência pública foi realizada nos dias 20 e 21 de maio de 2010 e a sentença condenatória, com data de 24 de novembro de 2010, só foi divulgada no dia 14 de dezembro de 2010. Importante registrar que foi somente após o anúncio da data aproximada da audiência pública na Corte IDH é que o STF colocou em pauta a ADPF 153. o artigo 2 desse instrumento, adotar todas as medidas para deixar sem efeito as disposições legais que poderiam contrariá-lo, como são as que impedem a investigação de graves violações de direitos humanos, uma vez que conduzem à falta de proteção das vítimas e à perpetuação da impunidade, além de impedir que as vítimas e seus familiares conheçam a verdade dos fatos. E de modo categórico, conclui a sentença: 174. Dada sua manifesta incompatibilidade com a Convenção Americana, as disposições da Lei de Anistia brasileira que impedem a investigação e sanção de graves violações de direitos humanos carecem de efeitos jurídicos. Em consequência, não podem continuar a representar um obstáculo para a investigação dos fatos do presente caso, nem para identificação e punição dos responsáveis, nem podem ter igual ou similar impacto sobre outros casos de graves violações de direitos humanos consagrados na Convenção Americana ocorridos no Brasil.35 Como se não bastasse a difícil convivência entre o Art. 1º, §1º da Lei Nº 6683/1979, quando interpretado como anistia a crimes de lesa humanidade, com a Constituição de 1988 e a Convenção Americana, há também o choque com a jurisprudência consolidada da Corte Interamericana de Direitos Humanos. Nos casos Barrios Altos36 e La Cantuta37 (Peru) e Almonacid Arelliano e outros38 (Chile) a Corte deixa patente que as anistias são incompatíveis com a Convenção Americana em casos de graves violações de direitos humanos, independentemente, inclusive, de se tratar ou não de auto-anistia ou de se ter ou não algum tipo de acordo neste sentido39. 35 CORTE INTERAMERICANA DE DIREITOS HUMANOS. Caso Gomes Lund e Outros ("Guerrilha do Araguaia") vs. Brasil. Sentença de 24 de novembro de 2010. Disponível em: . Acesso em 25 de ago. de 2013. 36 CORTE INTERAMERICANA DE DIREITOS HUMANOS. Caso Barrios Alto vs. Peru. Sentença de 14 de março de 2001. Disponível em: . Acesso em 25 de ago. de 2013. 37CORTE INTERAMERICANA DE DIREITOS HUMANOS. Caso La Cantuta vs. Peru. Sentença de 30 de novembro de 2007. Disponível em: . Acesso em 25 de ago. de 2013. 38 CORTE INTERAMERICANA DE DIREITOS HUMANOS. Caso Almonacid Arellano y otros vs. Chile. Sentença de 26 de setembro de 2006. Disponível em: . Acesso em 25 de ago. de 2013. 39 Em outro texto procurou-se assinalar que no caso brasileiro o fato de a anistia ter se voltado tanto para perseguidos políticos como para perseguidores não elimina o caráter de auto-anistia da Lei Nº 6683/1979, visto que a anistia aos agentes da ditadura era algo imposto pela ditadura e inegociável. Além disso, argumentou-se igualmente que, para o bem da história, não houve nenhum acordo digno deste nome. Ver: SILVA FILHO, José Carlos Moreira da . O Julgamento da ADPF 153 pelo Supremo Tribunal Federal e a Inacabada Transição Democrática Brasileira. In: Wilson Ramos Filho. (Org.). Trabalho e Regulação - as lutas sociais e as condições materiais da democracia. Belo Horizonte-MG: Fórum, 2012, v. 1, p. 129-177 Ao se submeter à competência da Corte Interamericana de Direitos Humanos em 1998, portanto antes do julgamento da ADPF 153, que se deu apenas em 2010, o Estado brasileiro reconheceu "como obrigatória, de pleno direito e sem convenção especial, a competência da Corte em todos os casos relativos à interpretação ou aplicação desta Convenção" (Art. 62, 1 da Convenção). Complementando, preconiza o Art. 62, 3 da Convenção que a Corte é o órgão competente para "conhecer de qualquer caso, relativo à interpretação e aplicação das disposições desta Convenção, que lhe seja submetido". Ainda, no Art. 68, 1 da Convenção está consignado que os "Estados-partes na Convenção comprometem-se a cumprir a decisão da Corte em todo caso em que forem partes". Surge daí o questionamento sobre o grau de vinculação do STF à jurisprudência da Corte IDH. Há quem afirme que esta vinculação só seria obrigatória caso estivesse expressamente prevista na Constituição ou na Convenção40. Ora, na Constituição de 1988, além do princípio da abertura do catálogo de direitos fundamentais no Art. 5º, §2º, há o Art. 7º do ADCT que prevê que "o Brasil propugnará pela formação de um tribunal internacional dos direitos humanos". Diante disto, é lógico pressupor que uma vez consolidada a submissão do país à jurisdição da Corte, ele deva respeito à sua jurisprudência ou ao menos a leve em consideração, especialmente quando ela está consolidada e representa interpretação mais favorável aos direitos humanos. Afinal o próprio STF já construiu e consolidou jurisprudência interna no sentido da prevalência da norma mais favorável aos direitos humanos. Por que este raciocínio vale para o caso da prisão do depositário infiel e não vale para o caso da anistia aos crimes de lesa humanidade? Importante também lembrar que a Convenção Americana, norma que vincula o Brasil, estabelece que a Corte é o órgão competente para interpretá-la (Art.62, 1 da Convenção). Talvez a única hipótese escusável de não alinhamento à jurisprudência da Corte seja quando ela não indique a interpretação ou norma mais favorável, quando o atendimento do princípio pro homine se dê a partir de interpretação divergente do STF, o que não é o caso, visto que se trata de não estender a anistia a crimes de lesa 40 É a posição sustentada em: VASCONCELOS, Eneas Romero de. O conflito entre Direito nacional e internacional: a jurisprudência da Corte Interamericana de Direitos Humanos vs. a jurisprudência do Supremo Tribunal Federal. Revista Anistia Política e Justiça de Transição, Ministério da Justiça, n.7, jan./jun 2012, Brasília, p.170-200. humanidade. Na ADPF 153 o voto do Ministro Celso de Mello, praticamente o único que menciona a jurisprudência da Corte IDH e a ela dá alguma atenção, tenta justificar a sua decisão favorável à validade da lei de anistia para casos de grave violação de direitos humanos diante da jurisprudência da Corte Interamericana. O seu argumento é que como a lei de anistia foi bilateral não se trata de auto-anistia, o que não resiste a um exame de lógica, pois como já se afirmou, o fato de que a anistia tenha alcançado perseguidos e perseguidores não elimina o fato de que a anistia a esses últimos foi fruto de uma imposição do governo ditatorial. Vê-se nitidamente, porém, que o Ministro não explorou a jurisprudência da Corte e não aprofundou a sua análise à luz do Direito Internacional dos Direitos Humanos, não se sabe porque razão, especialmente quando se aprecia seu rico voto no leading case da ilicitude da prisão do depositário infiel41. E, como já se assinalou acima, em acordo com a jurisprudência da Corte IDH, mesmo que não se tratasse de auto-anistia não seria lícito que ela alcançasse crimes de lesa humanidade. É como restou consignado na sentença da Corte IDH no Caso Gomes Lund: 176. Este Tribunal estabeleceu em sua jurisprudência que é consciente de que as autoridades internas estão sujeitas ao império da lei e, por esse motivo, estão obrigadas a aplicar as disposições vigentes no ordenamento jurídico. No entanto, quando um Estado é parte de um tratado internacional, como a Convenção Americana, todos os seus órgãos, inclusive seus juízes, também estão submetidos àquele, o que os obriga a zelar para que os efeitos das disposições da Convenção não se vejam enfraquecidos pela aplicação das normas contrárias a seu objeto e finalidade, e que desde o início carecem de efeitos jurídicos. O Poder Judiciário, nesse sentido, está internacionalmente obrigado a exercer um "controle de convencionalidade" ex officio entre as normas 41 Afirmou o Ministro em seu voto no HC 87.585 que "a relação de eventual antinomia entre os tratados internacionais em geral (que não versem o tema dos direitos humanos) e a Constituição da República impõe que se atribua, dentro do sistema de direito positivo vigente no Brasil, irrestrita precedência hierárquica à ordem normativa consubstanciada no texto constitucional, ressalvadas as hipóteses excepcionais previstas nos §§2º e 3º do art. 5º da própria Lei Fundamental, que conferem hierarquia constitucional aos tratados internacionais de direitos humanos. (...) É preciso ressalvar, no entanto, como precedentemente já enfatizado, as convenções internacionais de direitos humanos celebradas antes do advento da EC nº 45/2004, pois, quanto a elas incide o §2º do art. 5º da Constituição, que lhes confere natureza materialmente constitucional, promovendo sua integração e fazendo com que se subsumam à noção mesma de bloco de constitucionalidade" (BRASIL. Supremo Tribunal Federal. Habeas Corpus Nº 87.585/TO. Paciente: Alberto de Ribamar Ramos Costa. Coator: Superior Tribunal de Justiça. Relator Ministro Marco Aurélio Mello. Brasília/DF: 03 de dezembro de 2008. Disponível em: . Acesso em 25 ago. 2013). internas e a Convenção Americana, evidentemente no marco de suas respectivas competências e das regulamentações processuais correspondentes. Nessa tarefa, o Poder Judiciário deve levar em conta não somente o tratado, mas também a interpretação que a ele conferiu a Corte interamericana, intérprete última da Convenção Americana. 177. No presente caso, o Tribunal observa que não foi exercido o controle de convencionalidade pelas autoridades jurisdicionais do estado e que, pelo contrário, a decisão do Supremo Tribunal Federal confirmou a validade da interpretação da Lei de Anistia, sem considerar as obrigações internacionais do Brasil derivadas do Direito Internacional (...)".42 A sentença da Corte IDH no Caso Araguaia, ainda que se queira arguir que a jurisprudência da Corte não vincule o Judiciário brasileiro ou que não imponha a ele ao menos uma obrigação de ser levada em consideração, revela uma vinculação indiscutível desse mesmo judiciário aos termos que condena o Estado do qual faz parte. Qual seria o propósito de o Brasil acatar a jurisdição da Corte se ele pudesse simplesmente desobedecer suas decisões se o seu judiciário assim entendesse? O Poder Judiciário não compõem o Estado? Não está consignado na Convenção que as decisões da Corte devem ser acatadas pelo Estado contra o qual ela se volta? A decisão do STF na ADPF 153, ainda não transitada em julgado, visto que sobre ela ainda pairam Embargos Declaratórios terá de ser revista e o bloqueio da Lei de Anistia afastado. Não há, à luz do Direito Internacional e dos princípios que amparam o Estado Democrático de Direito da República Federativa do Brasil, outra conclusão possível. 6. Considerações finais: A transição política no Brasil ainda está inacabada, mesmo já tendo passado vinte e cinco anos da promulgação da Constituição de 1988. A análise das ações do Estado brasileiro – principalmente no que diz respeito às dimensões da reforma das instituições e da responsabilização – revelam-se insuficientes para que seja possível reconhecer uma ruptura com os paradigmas autoritários instaurados em 1964. A pesquisa sobre as oportunidades que o STF teve de se pronunciar a respeito de temas envolvendo o tema da justiça de transição revela o papel de destaque que assume 42 CORTE INTERAMERICANA DE DIREITOS HUMANOS. Caso Gomes Lund e Outros ("Guerrilha do Araguaia") vs. Brasil. Sentença de 24 de novembro de 2010. Disponível em: . Acesso em 25 de ago. de 2013. o julgamento da ADPF Nº 153. A análise das contradições existentes entre a decisão desse julgamento e dos demais precedentes analisados demonstra que o Egrégio Tribunal proferiu – na ocasião do julgamento da ADPF Nº 153 – uma decisão predominantemente política, com fracos fundamentos jurídicos, que contraria os valores constitucionais vigentes. Certo está que toda decisão de um órgão jurisdicional é – também – uma decisão política. No entanto, a Constituição Federal – que apresenta as escolhas e diretrizes políticas construídas pela Assembleia Constituinte – limita a decisão dos órgãos dos poderes da República, inclusive do Judiciário. É com base naqueles valores elencados na Carta de 1988 que os magistrados devem encontrar a solução para os conflitos trazidos aos tribunais. Quando houve o julgamento da ADPF Nº 153, o STF deu força aos paradigmas que vigoravam no período anterior à instauração do Estado Democrático de Direito, retirando a força imperativa do texto constitucional. A posição adotada pelo STF, é preciso enfatizar, corrobora o entendimento de que a aliança existente durante o regime militar e os órgãos do Poder Judiciário permanece condicionando os avanços dos mecanismos de justiça transicional. Se por um lado a judicialização da repressão política no Brasil – materializada na busca do regime militar em levar a julgamento os seus opositores políticos – diminuiu a ocorrência de penalizações extrajudiciais (em comparação com as ditaduras do Cone Sul) durante o Estado de Exceção, por outro ainda se sofre com a convalidação, por parte de muitos magistrados, do simulacro de legalidade forjado pela ditadura civil-militar brasileira. A responsabilização dos crimes da ditadura sofreu, no julgamento da ADPF Nº 153, substancial prejuízo já que a decisão proferida tem efeito vinculante e eficácia erga omnes. Além disso, o próprio recurso de Embargos Declaratórios que aguarda julgamento já possui a sua esfera de abrangência limitada, uma vez que questiona a possibilidade de persecução criminal apenas dos crimes permanentes – homicídios, torturas, estupros e todos os outros crimes estão, conforme a lógica do “acordo bilateral” - anistiados. Os efeitos dessa postura do Estado brasileiro revelam-se ainda mais perversos: a cultura de impunidade dos crimes de lesa-humanidade faz aumentar – por parte das forças de segurança pública do país – o desrespeito pelos direitos humanos. A lógica do direito penal do inimigo segue fazendo suas vítimas no Estado Democrático de Direito43. Há, ainda nesse cenário, a necessidade de se considerar o fato de que o Brasil deve encontrar um modo de cumprir a condenação que sofreu na Corte Interamericana de Direitos Humanos após o julgamento da ADPF Nº 153 no Caso Gomes Lund. A Corte Interamericana foi taxativa ao reconhecer a nulidade da anistia brasileira e que ela não pode impedir a responsabilização de crimes de lesa-humanidade. Embora alguns Ministros já tenham se pronunciado informalmente defendendo que a Corte Interamericana não é órgão revisor das decisões do STF, o fato é que a questão segue sem solução. O descumprimento da sentença da Corte Interamericana pelo Brasil, em tese, poderia gerar sanções de direito internacional. Não parece que isso seja uma preocupação dos agentes políticos brasileiros. Aliás, tomando como referência os próprios Ministros do STF, a análise dos votos da ADPF Nº 153 revela um grande desprezo por toda a construção acerca do jus cogens, característico das normas de Direito Internacional, atitude contraditória com o próprio posicionamento anterior da Suprema Corte, o que situa a Lei Nº 6.683/1979 como um grande "tabu jurídico" para o Judiciário brasileiro. 7. Referências bibliográficas: ABRÃO, Paulo; TORELLY, Marcelo D. As dimensões da Justiça de Transição no Brasil, a eficácia da Lei de Anistia e as alternativas para a verdade e a justiça. In: ABRÃO, Paulo; PAYNE, Leigh; TORELLY, Marcelo. A Anistia na Era da Responsabilização: o Brasil em perspectiva internacional e comparada. Brasília: Ministério da Justiça, 2010. ABRÃO, Paulo. (Org.) ; VIEIRA, Jose Ribas (Org.) ; LOPES, J. R. L. (Org.) ; TORELLY, M. D. (Org.). Dossiê: o que é justiça de transição? In: Revista Anistia Política e Justiça de Transição, Brasília, n.1, p.31-112, jan.-jun. 2009. Ações Educativas da Comissão de Anistia - relatório de gestão 2007-2010. Brasília: Ministério da Justiça, 2010. AMNISTIA INTERNACIONAL BRASIL. “Entrán Disparando”: La actuación policial em las 43 Afirma relatório da Human Rights Watch que, “Segundo dados oficiais, as polícias dos estados do Rio de Janeiro e de São Paulo mataram juntas um total de mais de 11.000 pessoas desde 2003. Em quase todos esses casos, a polícia relatou que as mortes teriam sido atos de legítima defesa em tiroteios com supostos criminosos. Em São Paulo esses casos são designados por 'resistência seguida de morte' e no Rio conhecidos como 'autos de resistência'. No entanto, uma análise detalhada dos autos, das declarações das autoridades e dados estatísticos sugere de forma contundente que uma parte significativa desses casos são na realidade execuções extrajudiciais” (HUMAN RIGHTS WACTH. Força letal: violência policial e segurança pública no Rio de Janeiro e em São Paulo. 2009. p.27. Disponível em: http://www.hrw.org/sites/default/files/reports/brazil1209ptwebwcover.pdf . Acesso em 25 de ago. de 2013). comunidades socialmente excluidas. Disponível em: http://www.amnesty.org/es/library/asset/AMR19/025/2005/es/d6c16d41-d49c-11dd-8a23- d58a49c0d652/amr190252005pt.html. Acesso em 07/01/2014. ASSUMPÇÃO, Eliane Maria Salgado (org.). O Direito na História: o caso das mãos amarradas. Porto Alegre: TRF 4a. Região, 2008. BAGGIO, Roberta Camineiro. Marcas da Memória: a atuação da Comissão de Anistia no campo das políticas públicas de transição no Brasil. In: Ciências Sociais Unisinos, São Leopoldo, Vol. 48, N. 2, p. 111-118, mai/ago 2012. BRASIL. Secretaria Especial dos Direitos Humanos. Comissão Especial sobre Mortos e Desaparecidos Políticos. Direito à verdade e à memória. Brasília: Secretaria Especial dos Direitos Humanos, 2007. BRASIL. Supremo Tribunal Federal. Ação de Descumprimento de Preceito Fundamental Nº 153/DF. Arguente: Conselho Federal da Ordem dos Advogados do Brasil. Arguidos: Presidente da República e Congresso Nacional. Relator Ministro Luis Fux. Brasília/DF: 29 de abril de 2010. Disponível em:. Acesso em 25 ago. 2013. BRASIL. Supremo Tribunal Federal. Ação de Descumprimento de Preceito Fundamental Nº 130/DF. Arguente: Partido Democrático Trabalhista. Arguidos: Presidente da República, Congresso Nacional, Federação Nacional dos Jornalistas Profissionais, Associação Brasileira de Imprensa e Artigo 19 Brasil. Relator Ministro Carlos Ayres Britto. Brasília/DF: 30 de abril de 2009. Disponível em: . Acesso em 25 ago. 2013. BRASIL. Supremo Tribunal Federal. Extradição Nº 974. Requerente: Governo da República Argentina. Extraditando: Manoel Cordeiro Piacentini. Relator Ministro Marco Aurélio Mello; Relator p/ acórdão Ministro Ricardo Lewandowski. Brasília/DF: 06 de agosto de 2009. Disponível em . Acesso em 25 ago. 2013. BRASIL. Supremo Tribunal Federal. Extradição Nº 1150. Requerente: Governo da República Argentina. Extraditando: Norberto Raul Tozzo. Relatora Ministra Carmem Lúcia. Brasília/DF: 19 de maio de 2011. Disponível em . Acesso em 25 ago. 2013. BRASIL. Supremo Tribunal Federal. Extradição Nº 1278. Requerente: Governo da República Argentina. Extraditando: Claudio Vallejos. Relator Ministro Gilmar Mendes. Brasília/DF: 18 de setembro de 2012. Disponível em . Acesso em 25 ago. 2013. BRASIL. Supremo Tribunal Federal. Habeas Corpus Nº 87.585/TO. Paciente: Alberto de Ribamar Ramos Costa. Coator: Superior Tribunal de Justiça. Relator Ministro Marco Aurélio Mello. Brasília/DF: 03 de dezembro de 2008. Disponível em: . Acesso em 25 ago. 2013. BRASIL. Supremo Tribunal Federal. Habeas Corpus Nº 466.343/SP. Recorrente: Banco Bradesco S/A. Recorrido: Luciano Cardoso Santos. Relator Ministro Cézar Peluso. Brasília/DF: 03 de dezembro de 2008. Disponível em: . Acesso em 25 ago. 2013. COELHO, Maria José H.; ROTTA, Vera (orgs.). Caravanas da Anistia: o Brasil pede perdão. Brasília: Ministério da Justiça; Florianópolis: Comunicação, Estudos e Consultoria, 2012. CORTE INTERAMERICANA DE DIREITOS HUMANOS. Caso Gomes Lund e Outros ("Guerrilha do Araguaia") vs. Brasil. Sentença de 24 de novembro de 2010. Disponível em: . Acesso em 25 de ago. de 2013. CORTE INTERAMERICANA DE DIREITOS HUMANOS. Caso Barrios Alto vs. Peru. Sentença de 14 de março de 2001. Disponível em: . Acesso em 25 de ago. de 2013. CORTE INTERAMERICANA DE DIREITOS HUMANOS. Caso La Cantuta vs. Peru. Sentença de 30 de novembro de 2007. Disponível em: . Acesso em 25 de ago. de 2013. CORTE INTERAMERICANA DE DIREITOS HUMANOS. Caso Almonacid Arellano y otros vs. Chile. Sentença de 26 de setembro de 2006. Disponível em: . Acesso em 25 de ago. de 2013. FAORO, Raymundo. A República inacabada. São Paulo: Globo, 2007. FILHO, Vladimir Brega; SANTOS, Roberto Lima. Os reflexos da “judicialização” da repressão política no Brasil no seu engajamento com os postulados da justiça de transição. In: Revista Anistia Política e Justiça de Transição. Brasília: Ministério da Justiça, n.1, jan-jun, 2009. HUGGINS, Martha Knisely; ZIMBARDO, Philip G.; HARITOS-FATOUROS, Mika. Operários da Violência – policiais torturadores e assassinos reconstroem as atrocidades brasileiras. Brasília: UnB, 2006. HUMAN RIGHTS WACTH. Força letal: violência policial e segurança pública no Rio de Janeiro e em São Paulo. 2009. Disponível em: http://www.hrw.org/sites/default/files/reports/brazil1209ptwebwcover.pdf . Acesso em 07/01/2014. INTERNATIONAL CENTER FOR TRANSITIONAL JUSTICE, ICTJ. Parecer tácnico sobre a natureza dos crimes de lesa-humanidade, a imprescritibilidade de alguns delitos e a proibição de anistias. In: Revista Anistia Política e Justiça de Transição. Brasília: Ministério da Justiça, n.1, jan-jun, 2009. JESUS, Maria Gorete Marques de. O crime de tortura e a justiça criminal: um estudo dos processos de tortura na cidade de São Paulo. São Paulo: IBCCRIM, 2010. (Monografias, 55). JOSÉ, Otto. Os torturadores anistiados – como está sendo aplicada a Lei de Anistia. Movimento, São Paulo, abr. 1980 apud TELES, Janaína de Almeida. As disputas pela interpretação da Lei de Anistia de 1979. In: Idéias. São Paulo, n.1, jan./jun., 2010. JUSTIÇA GLOBAL. Execuções Sumárias, Arbitrárias e Extrajudiciais. Uma aproximação da realidade brasileira. Disponível em: http://dhnet.org.br/dados/relatorios/r_jglobal/r_jg_exec_extra_judiciais1.pdf. Acesso em 07/01/2014 JUSTIÇA GLOBAL. Segurança, Tráfico e Milícias no Rio de Janeiro. Disponível em: http://global.org.br/wp-content/uploads/2009/12/Relatorio_Milicias_completo.pdf . Acesso em 07/01/2014. MEYER, Emilio Peluso Neder. Ditadura e Responsabilização - elementos para uma justiça de transição no Brasil. Belo Horizonte: Arraes, 2012. p.68-75. NAÇÕES UNIDAS – Conselho de Segurança. O Estado de Direito e a justiça de transição em sociedades em conflito ou pós-conflito. Relatório do Secretário Geral S/2004/616. In: Revista Anistia Política e Justiça de Transição, Brasília, n.1, p.320-351, jan.-jun. 2009. p.325. NUCLEO DE ESTUDOS DE CIDADANIA, CONFLITO E VIOLÊNCIA (UFRJ). “Autos de" resistência: uma análise dos homicídios cometidos por policiais na cidade do Rio de Janeiro (2001-2011). Disponível em: http://www.necvu.ifcs.ufrj.br/images/Relatorio%20final%20Autos%20de%20Resist%C3%AAn cia.pdf Acesso em: 07/01/2014 OLSEN, Tricia D.; PAYNE, Leigh; REITER, Andrew G. As implicações políticas dos processos de anistia. In: ABÃO, Paulo; PAYNE, Leigh; TORELLY, Marcelo. A Anistia na Era da Responsabilização: o Brasil em perspectiva internacional e comparada. Brasília: Ministério da Justiça, 2010. OLSEN, Tricia D.; PAYNE, Leigh; REITER, Andrew G. Transitional Justice in Balance - comparing processes, weighing efficacy. Washington, D.C.: United States Institute of Peace Press, 2010. PAIXÃO, Cristiano. A constituição em disputa: transição ou ruptura? In: SEELAENDER, Airton (Org.) História do Direito e construção do Estado. São Paulo: Quartier Latin, 2012. no prelo. PEREIRA, Antrhony W. Ditadura e repressão: o autoritarismo e o estado de direito no Brasil, no Chile e na Argentina. São Paulo: Paz e Terra, 2010. RIO GRANDE DO SUL. Tribunal de Justiça. Câmara Criminal Especial. Recurso Crime n.16.336. Negado provimento em 01/10/1975. Relator: Cristovam Daiello Moreira. SANTOS, Roberto Lima; BREGA FILHO, Vladimir. Os reflexos da "judicialização" da repressão política no Brasil no seu engajamento com os postulados da justiça de transição. In: Revista Anistia Política e Justiça de Transição. Brasília, n.1, p.152-177, jan./jun. 2009. SIKKINK, Kathryn. The Justice Cascade - how human rights procesutions are changing world politics. New York, London: W.W. Norton & Company, 2011. SIKKINK, Kathryn. WALLING, Carrie Booth. The impact of human rights trials in Latin America. Journal of Peace Research, Los Angeles, London, New Delhi, Singapore, vol.44, n.4, 2007, p.427-445. SILVA FILHO, José Carlos Moreira da . O Julgamento da ADPF 153 pelo Supremo Tribunal Federal e a Inacabada Transição Democrática Brasileira. In: Wilson Ramos Filho. (Org.). Trabalho e Regulação - as lutas sociais e as condições materiais da democracia. Belo Horizonte-MG: Fórum, 2012, v. 1, p. 129-177. SILVA FILHO, José Carlos Moreira da. O terrorismo de Estado e a ditadura civil-militar no Brasil: direito de resistência não é terrorismo. Revista Anistia Política e Justiça de Transição, Ministério da Justiça, n.5, jan/jul 2011, Brasília, p.50-74. SILVA FILHO, José Carlos Moreira da . Crimes do Estado e Justiça de Transição. Sistema Penal & Violência, v. 2, p. 22-35, 2010. SOARES, Inês Virgínia Prado; KISHI, Sandra Akemi Shimada (coords.). Memória e verdade – a justiça de transição no estado democrático de direito. São Paulo: Fórum, 2009. SYKES, Gresham M.; MATZA, David. Techniques of neutralization: a theory of delinquency. In: American Sociological Review, n.22, 1957, p.664-670. VASCONCELOS, Eneas Romero de. O conflito entre Direito nacional e internacional: a jurisprudência da Corte Interamericana de Direitos Humanos vs. a jurisprudência do Supremo Tribunal Federal. Revista Anistia Política e Justiça de Transição, Ministério da Justiça, n.7, jan./jun 2012, Brasília, p.170-200. ZAFFARONI, Eugenio Raul. La palabra de los muertos - conferencias de criminologia cautelar. Buenos Aires: EDIAR, 2011. work_fm5bfayekfbmxarolod7doc3gq ---- L A N G U A G E P L A N N İN G : H E G E M O N Y OR S O C İA L J U S T IC E ? Kutlay Y ağmur M iddle E ast Technical University The practices of Language Planning and Policy Making is highly polemical in multilingual communities. In this paper we will examine Language Planning in terms of the principles of "Language Rights" and "Language Hegemony". The issues discussed in this paper are widespread throughout the world. IN T R O D U C T I O N In this p ap er we are going to review two articles in relation to L anguage Planning and L a n g u a g e R ights' in the U nited States o f A m erica, C alifornia. In these two opposing articles, 'for' and 'against' argum ents are raised in relation to the latest 'E n g lish L an g u ag e A m en d m en t/ P roposition 63' in C alifo rn ia. W hile E duardo H e rn a n d e z -C h a v e z l (1988) raises issues against Proposition 63, C onnie D yste^ (1989) argues m ainly for the Proposition. In the history o f m ultilingual societies, the struggle for survival o f the m inority languages against the dom inance o f the m ajority language is a never ending story and U nited States is a typical exam ple for that situation. In this struggle L anguage Planning and Policy M aking plays an im portant role in the structure o f pow er and (in )eq u ality th ro u g h o u t the w orld, especially in m u ltilin g u al so cieties like the U .S.A ., C anada, A ustralia, U.K., and form er U SSR. L an g u ag e P lan n in g is defined by T ollefson^ (1991) as the p lanners' conscious efforts to influence the structure or function o f language/s. These deliberate efforts m ight involve language purification, language revival (H ebrew ), language reform (Turkish), language standardization (Swahili), and language m odem ization (Swedish) 1 Hemandez-Chavez, E. 1988. 'Language Policy and Language Rights in the United States' in T. Skutnabb-Kangas & J. Cummins (eds.) Minority Education: From Shame to Struggle. Clevedon: Multilingual Matters. ^Dyste, C. 1989. 'Proposition 63: The California English Language Amendment', Applied Linguistics, 10-3. ■^Tollefson, J.W. 1991. Planning Language, Planning Inequality. London: Longman. Dilbilim Araştırmaları 1995 97 (E astm an, 1983)*. Therefore language planning practices are view ed from different perspectives in m onolingual and m ultilingual societies. It is clear that depending on the situation in a country or in a speech com m unity language planning m ay take different forms. O n the o th er hand, L an g u ag e P olicy is defin ed as "the in s titu tio n a liz a tio n o f lan g u ag e as a basis for d istin ctio n s am ong soeial groups o r elasses" (T o llefso n , 1991). L a n g u ag e p o lic y is seen as a m e c h a n ism fo r the e s ta b lis h m e n t o f "hegem ony" by the dom inant group/s. A s claim ed by A pple and M u y s k e n ^ (1987), language planning does not take place in a soeial vacuum . It is affected by m any facto rs like: so e ia l d em o g ra p h ic fa c to r s im plicating the n u m b er o f lan g u ag e s spoken, the num ber o f their speakers, geographical distribution; linguistic fa c to r s im p lic a tin g the status o f th e lan g u ag e /s (degree o f in tern atio n al use, literary tradition, ete.); the so cio -p sych o lo g ica l fa c to r s concerning the attitudes o f people tow ards a language, soeial m eanings attached to various languages; the p o litic a l fa c t o r s w hich are the m ost influential in language planning; and fınally, relig io u s fa c to r s the use o f local languages in the spread o f religion, for instance, the spread o f A rabic through İslam (W ardhaugh, 1987)3. x h o se five factors proposed by A pple & M uysken (1987: 56-57) are pertaining to 'Status planning' (decision procedures) but it is only the first step in language planning as there are also C orpus P la n n in g (C odifıcation and Standardization procedures); im plem entation (educational spread); and fınally, Elaboration (functional development). O n the other hand, K aplan (cited in B ald au f 1988: 16)^ points out that language plan n in g is alw ays open to the influence o f key individuals, bureaucratic struetures and in stitu tio n s, w hich act as 'intervening variables' in the lan g u ag e p la n n in g p ro c e s s. S om e o f those v a ria b le s are stated as p erceiv ed eco n o m ic d em an d , in stru m en tal benefits (source o f inform ation, scientific ex ch an g e), n atio n alism , e th n ic id e n tity , relig io n , h isto rical facto rs, the gro w th o f u rb a n iz a tio n , and b u reau cracies and education (B aldauf, 1988). L ike A pple & M u y sk en 's fa c to r s , K ap lan 's in terven in g v a ria b le s relate very closely to status plan n in g (decision procedures). ̂Eastman, C. 1983. Language Planning: An Introduction. San Francisco: Chandler & Sharp. ■^Appel, R. & P. Muysken. 1988. Language Contact and Bilingualism. London: Edward Amold. ^Wardhaugh, R. 1987. Languages in Competition: Dominance, Diversity, and Decline. London: Basil Blackwell. ^Baldauf, R.B. & A. Luke. 1988. Language Planning and Education in Australasia and the South Pacific. Clevedon: Multilingual Matters. 98 Yağmur H o w ev er, o u r m ain co n cern w ill be d e m o n stra tin g the m an ip u lab le nature o f language as it is subject to social and political pressures. T he articles chosen for this discussion illustrate the H egem onic P rin cip le o f language planning (D yste, 1989) and Social Jııstice Principle (Hem andez-Chavez, 1988). H egem ony Principle is discussed by T ollefson (1991) along with Skutnabb-K angas (1986)1, anj phillipson (1988)^ from a m inority perspective. Tollefson claim ed that "people who speak the p referred variety d eserve to be in p ositions o f authority a nd p o w e r a n d to control p o litica l and econom ic institutions. (...) To the extetıt that this fe e lin g o f naturalness o f language use becom es pervasive, the dom inant group has established hegem ony, w hich is the su ccessfu lp ro d u ctio n o f ideology." A chievem ent o f hegem ony is m ost con trov ersial in m ultilingual and industrialized societies; w hereas the hegem ony o f certain languages, nam ely English, is not only tolerated by the 'developing' coun tries but also considered a legitim ate m odel for society (T ollefson, 1991). H owever, in countries like the U SA , U.K., and A ustralia the struggle o f ethnic groups to m aintain their m other tongue is very closely tied to econom ic and political policies o f those countries. Even though G iles (1977)3 and his follow ers claim that ethnolinguistic vitality o f the groups determ ine the survival o f m in o rity languages, T ollefson (1991) su g g ests that the survival o f m inority languages is not sim ply a function o f the 'internal vitality' o f m inority groups, but ra th e r the stren g th o f the d o m in an t group and the h isto rical con seq u en ces o f hegem ony. Fishm an (1989)^ also com m ents on the m atter that there is no d o u b t in my mirıd that language a n d ethnicity in A m erica can n o t m ake it on their own, in terms o fp u b l ic p o licy a n d at p u b lic expense, both because they are too w eak and also because the opposition to them is ready-made and therefore ever-ready. On the other hand, H ernandez-C havez's (1988) paper calls into question the social- ju s tic e issue o f L anguage Planning m ainly on the hum anitarian grounds. Skutnabb- 1 Skutnabb-Kangas, T. & R. Phillipson. 1986. 'Denial of Linguistic Rights: The New Mental Slavery' paper presented at l l t h VVorld Congress of Sociology, New Delhi, India. -Phillipson, R. 1988. ’Linguicism: structures and ideologies in Linguistic Imperialism' in T. Skutnabb-Kangas & J. Cummins (eds.) Minority Education: From Shatne to Struggle. Clevedon: Multilingual Matters. "Giles, H. (ed.) 1977. Language, Ethnicity and Intergroup Relations. London: Academic Press. ^Fishman, J. 1988. Language & Ethnicity in Minority Sociolinguistic Perspective. Clevedon: Multilingual Matters. Dilbilim Araştırmaları 1995 99 K angas (1986) claim s that "different languages have different p olitical rights, n o t by v ir tu e o f a n y in h e r e n t lin g u istic characteristics, b u t d e p e n d e n t on the p o w e r rela tio n sh ip s betw een the sp ea kers o f those la n g u a g es.” She claim s th at unless m inority languages have offıcial use (as the m edium o f instruction in schools), they will not survive; that is w hy, there has to be legislation openly prom oting m inority languages vvithin a 'm aintenance-oriented' framevvork. Sim ilarly, P hillipson (1989) claim s that L in g u icism is the very threat to L anguage R ights o f m inorities because "the ideologies a n d structures w hich are used to legitimate, effectuate a nd reproduce an urıequal division o fp o w e r and resources between groups are d efined on the basis o f lang u a g e”, th at o f hegem ony. B A C K G R O U N D TO T H E STUD İES U N D ER C O N SID ER A TIO N As sum m arized in detail both by D yste (1989) and H ernandez-C havez (1988), there have been so m any attem pts to regulate the role o f language since C alifornia ceded from M exico to the U .S.A . in 1849. T he Treaty m ade in that tim e p ro m ised that E nglish and S panish w ould be given equal status in the operations o f governm ent and education in that region. H ow ever, after one and a h a lf a century, the E nglish L an g u ag e is ch o sen to be the offıcia l language o f the S tate, w hich is the fırst legislature act in the history o f the U nited State. In other States, E nglish is given a sy m b o lic reco g n itio n ; b u t P ro p o sitio n 63 is an offıcial leg islatio n , the ro le o f w hich is defined as follovvs: It requires the Legislature to take ali steps necessary to ensure that the role o f E nglish as the com m on language o f the State o f C alifornia is p reserved a n d enhanced, a n d to m ake no law which dim inishes o r ignores the role o f E nglish as the com m on language o f the State o f California. (D yste, 1989). H ow ever, the m o st im portant aspect o f the Proposition 63 is that rather than being a top-dow n act, the legislation was initiated by certain pressure groups and voted by the m ajority o f the public on the grounds that E nglish m ust be the only dom inant language in C alifo rn ia. On the o th er hand, as discussed in detail by H ernandez- C havez (1988), in the history o f the U .S.A ., there have been m any cases o f the use o f m inority languages in public places, schools, courts, ete. being banned due to v arious reasons. M ainly in tim es o f crises, banning o f m inority languages and diserim inatory m oves w ere very comm on. 100 Yağmur A r g u m e n ts fo r P r o p o s itio n 63 D y ste (1 9 8 9 ) a rg u es for P ro p o sitio n 63 by cla im in g th at u n le ss E n g lish is g iv en th e o ffic ia l sta tu s, A m e r ic a 's fu tu r e m ig h t be in je o p a r d y due to e th n ic strife. S he gives a long account o f the history o f the argum ents for E nglish to be the o fficial language o f C alifornia. D y ste structures her argum ent around the concept o f N ation al U nity. D yste's argum ent can be sum m arized as follovvs: X the U .S .A . has alvvays been a m o n o lin g u a l, E n g lish -sp e a k in g country; bilingual education and bilingual voting rights threaten dom inant State o f E nglish language by introducing language divisions vvhich vvill gradually displace E nglish; X today's im m igrants' are different from those o f the p ast as they com e from L atin A m erica and A sia and they are unvvilling to learn English; X use o f ethnic languages other than English delays the econom ic, cultural and linguistic assim ilation o f those im m igrants; X m ultilingualism threatens the political and cultural unity o f the U.S.A. A r g u m e n ts A g a in s t P r o p o s itio n 63 In his argum en ts ag ain st P roposition 63, H ernan d ez-C h av ez raises som e issues m ainly on the social ju stice principle and hum anitarian grounds. H e claim s that language on a cultural level is "the sym b o lic expression o f com m unity erıcoding a g ro u p 's values, its folkvvays a n d its history. Socially, language is the m ost p o w erfu l rneans o f in te ra c tio n a n d co m m u n ica tio n ; a n d it is th ro u g h la n g u a g e th a t an individual o r a group seeks and attains participation in society. The denial o f a peo p le's developm ent and use o f its native tongue is thus a d enial o f its participation in society a n d o f its very peoplehood. " H ernandez-C havez defınes language rights as the right o f a people to learn, to keep and use its own language in ali m anner o f public and private affairs and that to do so is a hum an right. Hovvever, he adds, the dom inant group Controls ali the institutions and develops m echanism s to lim it the access o f m inority groups to services, and Dilbilim Araştırmaları 1995 101 oppo rtu n ities av ailable to people. B ecause o f the barriers, he claim s, ethnic group m em bers can not participate in ali m anner o f life; and finally, he adds that since the m inority groups can not attain a level o f proficiency, their right to participate in life and enjoy the sam e rights as others is ignored. He adds th at even if they acquire a high co m p eten ce in the d o m in an t gro u p 's language, som e other barriers to full access will be faced. In his final analysis, H ern an d ez-C h av ez hig h lig h ts the im portance o f b ilin g u al education fo r ethnic groups. H e believes m o th er tongue teaching w ould function as tra n sitio n to E n g lish and the p u rp o se is m o re e ffe c tiv e teac h in g o f E n g lish . H ow ever, he adds, the opponents o f b ilin g u al education claim s that it is sim ply m a in ta in in g the lan g u ag es and cu ltu res o f ethnic m in o rities at p u b lic expense. M o reo v er, he claim s, both the p ro p o n en ts and opp on ents o f bilingual education ignore the fact that learning one's native tongue is a right. Finally, he argues that if the native language has not been developed, the child loses a pow erful m eans o f learning. In short, the child under these con d itio n s is denied the rig h t to an equal ed u catio n al o p p o rtu n ity eq ually as im p o rta n t, the failu re to d ev elo p the hom e lan g u ag e is often a cause o f alienation betvveen children, their parents and their com m unity. C O N C L U S I O N A s we have seen the argum ents fo r and ag ain st can be grouped around the social ju s tic e ’e q u ity ' p rin c ip le and h eg em ony p rin c ip le o f L an g u ag e P lan n in g . T h e argum ents fo r the banning o f m inority languages claim ed that m inority language teaching m ig h t be a potential th reat to th e status o f E nglish vvhich could lead to tu rm o il in th e co u n try , and the only so lu tio n is m ak in g E n g lish the o ffıcia l lan g u ag e o f the State and fo rcin g eth n ic gro u p s to learn E n g lish by b a n n in g languages other than English. T hey also believe that bilingual education is a barrier to full participation and com plete assim ilation for ethnic children. O n the other hand, the argum ents against Proposition 63 claim that speaking one's m o th er to n g u e is a hum an right and the use o f a child's language is som ething to vvhich s/he is m orally entitled to. It is im p o rtan t to note that Proposition 63 passed by a margin of 73 percent to 27 percent vvhich shovvs strong p reference fo r the hegem ony o f English am ong people. People voted and by doing that they announced th at lan g u ag es o th er than E nglish m ust be banned. T he strongest su pporters o f P ro p o sitio n 63 vvere "whites, the less educated, a n d co n serva tiv es; vvhile the opponents w ere H ispanics andA sians, highly educated, and Liberals." It is quite clear that even in a country like the U .S .A ., w here H um an R ig h ts are v alu ed the m ost, languages other than E nglish can be banned. A nd in doin g that th e y c la im e d th a t th e p o lit ic a l a n d c ıılt u r a l u n ity o f th e S t a t e is th r e a te n e d . R E F E R E N C E S A ppel, R. & P. M uysken. 1988. Language C ontact a n d B ilingualism . London: Edward Amold. B aldauf, R. B. & A. Luke. 1988. Language Planning a nd Education in A usîralasia a n d the South Pacific. C levedon: M ultilingual M atters. D yste, C. 1989. Proposition 63: The C alifornia E nglish L anguage A m endm ent, A p p lie d L inguistics, 10-3. E astm an, C. 1983. Language P lanning: A n Introduction. San Francisco: C handler & Sharp. F ishm an, J. 1988. Language & E thnicity in M inority Sociolinguistic P erspective. C levedon: M ultilingual M atters. G iles, H. (Ed.) 1977. Language, Ethnicity, a n d Intergroup Relatiotıs. London: A cadem ic Press. H em andez-C havez, E. 1988. 'Language Policy and L anguage R ights in the U nited States' in T. Skutnabb-K angas & J. C um m ins (Eds.) Minority- E ducation: F rom Sham e to Strııggle. Clevedon: M ultilingual M atters. Skutnabb-K angas. T. & R. Phiilipson. 1986. 'Denial o f L inguistic R ights: T he N ew M ental Slavery' paper presented at 1 lth W orld C ongress o f Sociology, Nevv Delhi, India. T ollefson, J.W . 1991. Planning Language, Planning Inequality. London: L ongm an. W ardhaugh, R. 1987. Languages in Competition: D om inance, D iversity, a nd D ecline. London: Basil Blackvvell. 102 Yağmur work_fokf7zqunzc4njukukslvbeboa ---- 10.1177/1059601104265054 ArticleGROUP & ORGANIZATION MANAGEMENTFoley et al. / PERCEPTIONS OF DISCRIMINATION AND JUSTICE Perceptions of Discrimination and Justice ARE THERE GENDER DIFFERENCES IN OUTCOMES? SHARON FOLEY Drexel University NGO HANG-YUE The Chinese University of Hong Kong ANGELA WONG The Chinese University of Hong Kong This article examines the relationship among perceived gender discrimination, organizational justice, and work-related attitudes (i.e., job satisfaction, organizational commitment, and inten- tions to leave) for a sample of Protestant clergy in Hong Kong. The moderating role of gender on the relationship is also explored. The results of regression analysis showed that (a) justice and discrimination perceptions were significantly related to job attitudes; (b) compared to men, women who perceived more gender discrimination had a lower level of organizational commit- ment; (c) compared to women, men who perceived more distributive justice had a higher level of job satisfaction; and (d) perceptions of justice influenced intentions to leave through their impact on job satisfaction and organizational commitment. Theoretical and practical implications are discussed. Keywords: gender discrimination; organizational justice; job attitudes; gender differences During the past decade, increasing research attention has been paid to per- ceived injustice and discrimination in management literature. Both per- ceived injustice and perceived discrimination are found to be associated with some negative outcomes. For example, perceived procedural injustice has been positively linked to retaliation against the organization (Skarlicki & Folger, 1997); perceived distributive injustice has been positively linked to Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to Sharon Foley, Department of Management, Drexel University, Philadelphia, PA, 19104; e-mail: sf46@drexel.edu. Group & Organization Management, Vol. 30 No. 4, August 2005 421-450 DOI: 10.1177/1059601104265054 © 2005 Sage Publications 421 employee theft (Greenberg, 1990); and perceived gender discrimination has been positively linked to work conflict (Gutek, Cohen, & Tsui, 1996). Although one published study focused on both perceived ethnic discrimi- nation and perceptions of distributive justice (Foley, Kidder, & Powell, 2002), few studies have examined perceived gender discrimination, proce- dural justice, and distributive justice together in one model, particularly in a non-Western setting. In addition, in the studies that have focused on gen- der differences in the reactions to justice or discrimination, the results from these studies have been mixed (Lee & Farh, 1999; Ngo, Tang, & Au, 2002; Sweeney & McFarlin, 1997). In the present study, we relate individuals’ perceived gender discrimina- tion, procedural justice, and distributive justice to their reactions to the job and to the organization, and we examine the moderating role of gender on these relationships in a non-Western setting. The purpose of this study is fourfold: (a) to provide a theoretical framework that links perceptions of jus- tice and gender discrimination to several salient job attitudes (i.e., job satis- faction, organizational commitment, and intentions to leave); (b) to extend the current literature by testing several new hypotheses about the moderating role of gender; (c) to test the mediating effect of work-related attitudes on the relationship between justice or discrimination perceptions and intentions to leave the organization; and (d) to assess the generalizability of research find- ings in Western settings by employing a non-Western sample. We examine the reactions of Protestant clergy in Hong Kong to perceptions of justice and gender discrimination. Similar to other professional occupations, the clergy has been male- dominated and male-controlled (Bock, 1967; McDuff & Mueller, 2002). There is clear evidence that female clergy experience inferior work condi- tions and suffer from workplace inequalities (Chang, 2000; McDuff, 2001; Nesbitt, 1996; Schneider & Schneider, 1997). The present study adds to the management literature by examining the outcomes of perceptions of gender discrimination and justice for professional workers. Also, using samples from other countries allows us to see whether American management theo- ries, which reflect American culture, are transferable to other countries (Hofstede, 1993). We apply theories from social psychology including social identity theory, social comparison, relative deprivation, and gender-role the- ory. Based on gender-role theory, we propose that men react more strongly to perceived justice in the workplace and women react more strongly to per- ceived gender discrimination. Attention to these matters is important for organizations concerned about attracting and retaining professionals of both genders. 422 GROUP & ORGANIZATION MANAGEMENT LITERATURE REVIEW PERCEIVED GENDER DISCRIMINATION AND SOCIAL COMPARISONS Gender discrimination is said to occur when personnel decisions are based on gender, an ascribed characteristic, rather than on an individual’s qualifications or job performance (Gutek et al., 1996; Ngo et al., 2002). Per- ceived discrimination is an individual’s perception that he or she is treated differently or unfairly because of his or her group membership (Sanchez & Brock, 1996). One’s identity group may include individuals with similar demographic characteristics, such as ethnicity, gender, or age (Ensher, Grant-Vallone, & Donaldson, 2001). When individuals perceive gender dis- crimination, they believe that members of their sex are systematically disad- vantaged at work relative to the other sex (Gutek et al., 1996). In assessing whether they are experiencing gender discrimination, indi- viduals often use social comparisons. Social comparisons provide informa- tion about what types of outcomes and/or treatments, such as salary increases or promotions, it is possible to achieve (Major, 1994). Collective relative deprivation refers to the grievance felt on behalf of one’s group and the reac- tions to those grievances, such as resentment and dissatisfaction (Crosby, 1982). Consistent with the theory of collective relative deprivation, women who perceived that their organization discriminated against their own sex (i.e., group deprivation) expressed their feelings in concrete ways, such as decreased self-efficacy (Gutek et al., 1996). DISTRIBUTIVE AND PROCEDURAL JUSTICE Distributive justice is grounded in equity theory, which states that individ- uals believe outcomes are fair when they are consistent with individual inputs (Adams, 1965; Folger & Cropanzano, 1998). Since justice refers to individuals’ perceptions of fairness, we will use the terms justice and fairness interchangeably. The fairness of the means used to determine organizational outcomes is referred to as procedural justice. Two central themes in the study of organizational justice are that fairness in organizational procedures consti- tutes both an important determinant of work attitudes (Lee & Farh, 1999) and a predictor of employee reactions, such as how individuals evaluate their workplace experiences (Sweeney & McFarlin, 1997). Justice researchers have generated a large body of research illustrating that justice perceptions have substantial effects on job satisfaction and organizational commitment (Cohen-Charash & Spector, 2001; Younts & Mueller, 2001). Foley et al. / PERCEPTIONS OF DISCRIMINATION AND JUSTICE 423 Employees’ perceptions of distributive and procedural justice are related to organizational policies and practices. According to Balser (2002), individ- uals’ interpretations and perceptions of discrimination are also affected by the practices and procedures, adopted by the organization, that signal stake- holders about the organization’s concerns for the fair treatment of employ- ees. Some organizational practices (e.g., lower pay for women) may simulta- neously affect the perceptions of distributive justice, procedural justice, and gender discrimination, whereas other practices (e.g., salary cut in a depart- ment) may affect only one perception. Although the perceptions of distribu- tive justice and gender discrimination involve social comparisons, the target of comparisons may not be the same. Therefore, the three constructs are different but related as they focus on different aspects of equity at work. GENDER AND CULTURAL DIFFERENCES Research examining gender differences in the justice/outcome relation- ship has shown mixed results. Brockner and Adsit (1986) found that per- ceived distributive justice had a stronger relationship with job satisfaction for men compared to women. Sweeney and McFarlin (1997) found that relation- ships between the fairness of procedures (e.g., performance appraisal) and various organizational outcome variables (e.g., commitment and intent to stay) are stronger for women than for men, and that relationships between the fairness of outcome distributions (e.g., pay raises) and those same variables are stronger for men than for women. Lee and Farh (1999) replicated Swee- ney and McFarlin’s study, and the only moderated effect they found was between distributive justice and trust in supervisor, which was stronger for women than for men. Fields, Pang, and Chiu (2000) found that the effects of procedural and distributive justice are about the same for men and for women, suggesting that women may expect to obtain fair treatment in the allocation of rewards. Brockner and Adsit (1986) were guided by the notion that if the equity norm is more salient for males than females, then males’ satisfaction with an exchange relationship would be more dependent upon the equity of that rela- tionship relative to females’ satisfaction. Lee and Farh (1999) suggested that females focus more on process-oriented issues, whereas males focus more on outcome-oriented issues. Sweeney and McFarlin (1997, p. 84) based their hypotheses on “the overall pattern of laboratory research and theorizing,” including women’s low sense of personal entitlement and women’s social- ization to be more interested in cultivating relationships with co-workers than are men. Fields et al. (2000) proposed that distributive and procedural justice will predict work outcomes in Hong Kong in the same way as in the 424 GROUP & ORGANIZATION MANAGEMENT U.S. (i.e., procedural justice will have a stronger relationship than distribu- tive justice with work outcomes for women). They took the viewpoint that Hong Kong’s exposure to Western business and employment practices has led to a convergence of work-related values and expectations despite sub- stantial cultural differences (i.e., differences in collectivism vs. individual- ism, power distance, and Confucianism). Thus, the relationships of justice and work outcomes for Hong Kong employees would be similar to rela- tionships found in previous studies of American employees. Rather than focusing on the above cultural differences, we propose that due to a similarly high masculinity score in Hong Kong and the United States, the relationship between distributive justice and various organiza- tional outcomes is stronger for men than for women. The level of masculinity versus femininity in a society is related to the division of gender roles and gender differences in values (Hofstede, 2001). In masculine societies, men are supposed to be assertive, competitive, and focused on material success, whereas women are supposed to be more modest, tender, and concerned with the quality of life (Hofstede, 1980, 2001). Studies have found that Chinese subjects show greater degrees of sex-role differentiation than Americans (Bond & Hwang, 1986). Therefore, we also expect that the relationship between procedural justice and outcome variables is stronger for men than for women. We suggest that a culture’s masculinity dimension may have sig- nificant consequences for the validity of applying theories of justice and discrimination from one country to another. GENDER ROLE THEORY AND PERSONAL RELATIVE DEPRIVATION One explanation for gender differences in reactions to justice or discrimi- nation that has not been fully explored is the social role theory of gender dif- ferences (or gender role theory). According to this theory, women and men tend to differ in a wide range of social behaviors in social contexts in which gender roles are salient (Eagly, 1987). Individuals conform to gender stereo- types (e.g., men exhibit traditionally masculine behaviors, and women ex- hibit traditionally feminine behaviors) in large part because the different roles that they perform place different social demands on them (Vogel, Wester, Heesacker, & Madon, 2003). Males, likely to be in higher-status roles, display gender-stereotypic “agentic” qualities (e.g., assertive, compet- itive, controlling), and females, likely to be in lower-status roles, display gender-stereotypic “communal” qualities (e.g., nurturing, kind, selfless) (Crosby, 1982, p. 16). The enactment of gender roles and the confirmation of gender stereotypes appear to be a dynamic process that is dependent on Foley et al. / PERCEPTIONS OF DISCRIMINATION AND JUSTICE 425 specific contextual factors (Vogel et al., 2003). Applying gender role theory, Fields et al.’s (2000) finding of no gender difference in the justice/outcome relationship may be due to specific social roles (e.g., occupational roles) that are of considerably more importance in determining work behavior than are gender roles. In other words, because such social roles may easily override gender roles under certain conditions, it is possible that women and men in the same specific social role behave quite similarly (Eagly, 1987). The general explanation for personal relative deprivation is that individu- als’ expectations, based largely on social comparisons, determine levels of contentment regardless of their objective situation. Whereas justice theory takes into account people’s feelings about distributions in general, relative- deprivation research concentrates on how people react to “their own position in the larger matrix” (Crosby, 1982, p. 26). Social comparisons are an essen- tial component in assessing whether one is deprived. Building on Crosby’s (1982) work, Major (1994) argued that women feel less entitled to job re- wards than do men, and that is the key to understanding women’s greater job satisfaction. SOCIAL IDENTITY THEORY The basic principles of social identity underlie much of the research on equity and justice theory (Primeaux, Karri, & Caldwell, 2003). Social iden- tity theory (Capozza & Brown, 2000; Tajfel & Turner, 1986) suggests that people classify themselves and others into social categories and then identify more with members of their own category (in-group) than with members of other categories (out-group). According to this perspective, identity has a social component derived from salient group memberships, such as gender, race, class, and nationality (Ashforth & Mael, 1989). People may identify more with individuals who are similar along a dimension of social identity that they believe has been used as the basis of discrimination against them (Wharton, 1992). Social identity theory suggests that females in the work- place may be sensitive to discrimination or injustice that they believe is directed toward women (Schmitt, Ellemers, & Branscombe, 2003) and that women’s own personal experiences or the experiences of others with whom they identify will affect their perception of discrimination (Gutek et al., 1996). Since Hong Kong is a masculine society where social gender roles are clearly distinct (Hofstede, 2001), we expect that individuals will identify with others along gender lines. In summary, perceptions of gender discrimination and justice, and the processes that generate these perceptions, occur within social contexts that often treat or reward people differently based on the social group to which 426 GROUP & ORGANIZATION MANAGEMENT they belong. Organizational characteristics, such as segregation and discrim- ination, are likely to structure comparison processes by shaping the relative value individuals attach to various social groups. Gender differences in work attitudes and behaviors are affected by many aspects of the organizational context, such as role expectations associated with one’s gender and job position. HYPOTHESES Figure 1 presents our proposed model of perceptions, attitudes, and inten- tions. Below, several hypotheses are derived for our Protestant clergy re- spondents in Hong Kong. DIRECT EFFECTS Employees who perceived sexist policies and practices in their organiza- tions reported less job satisfaction and organizational commitment (Ensher et al., 2001) and are less likely to choose the same career if they could start over (Gutek et al., 1996). Discrimination against female clergy is demon- strated by their disproportionate absence from positions of authority, their assignment to specialized positions with less chance of promotions, and lower salaries than male colleagues receive (Nesbitt, 1997; Ngo, Foley, Wong, & Loi, 2003; Schneider & Schneider, 1997). In addition, studies of male and female clergy consistently find a gender gap in benefits and pay Foley et al. / PERCEPTIONS OF DISCRIMINATION AND JUSTICE 427 Job Satisfaction Organizational Commitment Intentions to Leave H1b, H2b, H3b H8a H8b H8a H1a, H2a, H3a H8b H5a, H5b, H6a, H6b, H7a, H7b Gender Perceived Gender Discrimination Distributive Justice Procedural Justice H4a, H4b, H4c Figure 1: Proposed Theoretical Model (Chang, 2000; McDuff, 2001). Female clergy as a group still face difficulties in being accepted by congregations, and female clergy have not integrated well into the occupation beyond lower-level positions (Nesbitt, 1997; Ngo & Wong, 2002). We predict that when individuals perceive that their gender is used as the basis of discrimination in their workplace, they will display a low level of job satisfaction and organizational commitment. Hypothesis 1a: Perceived gender discrimination will be negatively related to job satisfaction. Hypothesis 1b: Perceived gender discrimination will be negatively related to orga- nizational commitment. It is well documented that when individuals perceive that the basic out- comes in their organization are more fair, they have more positive work- related attitudes (Greenberg, 1986, 1990). Individuals make social compari- sons between themselves and their coworkers in regards to their organizational rewards. These comparisons are likely to influence their assessment of the fairness of rewards in their organization (Ngo et al., 2003), which in turn affects their level of job satisfaction and commitment to the organization. Hypothesis 2a: Perceived distributive justice will be positively related to job satisfaction. Hypothesis 2b: Perceived distributive justice will be positively related to organi- zational commitment. One of the most consistent and significant findings of procedural justice research is the positive effect perceptions of procedural justice exert on indi- viduals’ long-term attitudes (such as commitment and satisfaction) toward groups, institutions, and leaders (Kim & Mauborgne, 1998). The manner in which a social system deals with allocating rewards and resources has an impact on organizational effectiveness and on the satisfaction of organiza- tional members (Leventhal, 1980). Randall and Mueller (1995) provide evi- dence of the positive effect of justice evaluations on job satisfaction and organizational commitment. Hypothesis 3a: Perceived procedural justice will be positively related to job satisfaction. Hypothesis 3b: Perceived procedural justice will be positively related to organiza- tional commitment. Intentions to leave have been studied extensively in the management liter- ature (e.g., Randall, Cropanzano, Bormann, & Birjulin, 1999). Most turn- over research has found that intentions to leave are the strongest predictor of 428 GROUP & ORGANIZATION MANAGEMENT employee turnover behavior (Rosin & Korabik, 1991; Stroh, Brett, & Reilly, 1996). Other organizational phenomena have been hypothesized to influ- ence intentions to leave the firm. For one sample of female managers, work- ing in a male-dominated environment was significantly related to low satis- faction and commitment and to a high propensity to leave the firm (Rosin & Korabik, 1991). Female managers leave their organizations because they “bump their heads” against a glass ceiling. Thus, perceived gender discrimi- nation will increase turnover intentions (Morrison, White, & Van Velsor, 1987). Stroh et al. (1996) also found that female managers who are frustrated at their lack of career opportunities are more likely to quit their organizations than are male managers with a similar level of frustration. Previous research has identified a link between organizational justice and intentions to leave (DeWitt, Trevino, & Mollica, 1998). Social comparisons (with others or self) affect wants, aspirations, and judgments of what is feasi- ble for oneself (Major, 1994), and when social comparison leads to feelings of unfairness, the individual may intend to leave the firm. As pointed out by McDuff and Mueller (2000), clergy intentions to leave one church for another are based on a rational assessment of work conditions in their current church. Thus, we predict that despite their professional service calling, clergy will seriously consider leaving their organization if they are experi- encing gender discrimination and unfairness in their church. Hypothesis 4a: Perceived gender discrimination will be positively related to inten- tions to leave. Hypothesis 4b: Perceived distributive justice will be negatively related to inten- tions to leave. Hypothesis 4c: Perceived procedural justice will be negatively related to inten- tions to leave. MODERATING EFFECT OF GENDER In the present study, we hypothesize that the relationship between per- ceived gender discrimination and work-related attitudes will differ for women and for men.1 Existing evidence indicates that women experience more gender discrimination in the workplace than do men (Northcraft & Gutek, 1993) and encounter a glass-ceiling barrier to promotion based on gender (Morrison et al., 1987). Some researchers contend that women tend to be more aware of employment discrimination than men owing to their mem- bership in a discriminated-against social group (Ngo et al., 2002; Trentham & Larwood, 1998). Although social identity theory and the concept of rela- tive deprivation suggests that women typically use other women as their so- cial comparison group (Crosby, 1982), women presumably compare them- Foley et al. / PERCEPTIONS OF DISCRIMINATION AND JUSTICE 429 selves to men when assessing gender discrimination. Working women can see that women in general are disadvantaged in the workplace. In other words, women easily recognize areas of collective disadvantage (Crosby, 1982). If women do indeed perceive more discrimination based on gender than do men, and if they expect to suffer more from it than do men, then the relationship between gender discrimination and negative reactions to the job and organization will be stronger for women than for men. Hypothesis 5a: Gender will moderate the relationship between perceived gender discrimination and job satisfaction. Specifically, the negative effect of per- ceived gender discrimination on job satisfaction will be stronger for women than for men. Hypothesis 5b: Gender will moderate the relationship between perceived gender discrimination and organizational commitment. Specifically, the negative effect of perceived gender discrimination on organizational commitment will be stronger for women than for men. Gender differences in entitlement for pay is an important reason why women are no less satisfied than men are with their jobs or pay despite their objective disadvantage (Major, 1994). Major (1994) argued that women feel less entitled to job rewards than men do and women’s sense of entitlement is likely to be affected by their acceptance of gender-based inequality in job rewards and conditions. The “contented female worker” sees little gap be- tween her actual and desired job rewards, even though she is underpaid rela- tive to men, because pay does not constitute a critical desire for her (Crosby, 1982, p. 160). Women and men estimate what they deserve on the basis of intragroup comparisons that occur in social contexts in which women are dis- advantaged, resulting in women having a lesser sense of entitlement to pay and rewards than men have (Major, 1994). Female clergy receive lower pay, serve in less desirable churches, and receive fewer opportunities for ad- vancement, yet they are significantly more satisfied with their jobs than are male clergy in comparable positions (McDuff, 2001). Among the Protestant clergy in Hong Kong, gender roles are salient and likely to override any specific social roles (e.g., organizational or profes- sional roles), and thus we would expect to find gender differences in justice/ outcome relationships. There are two reasons for the gender differences. First, female clergy have fewer opportunities for promotion and ordination compared to male clergy, and they have a lower representation in large denominations (Nesbitt, 1996; Ngo & Wong, 2002). According to McDuff and Mueller (2002), under such circumstances, female clergy tend to develop alternative models of ministry. For example, they may be expanding the images of ways to perform the ministry and reevaluating traditional values 430 GROUP & ORGANIZATION MANAGEMENT about their profession. In ambiguous work situations that lack well-defined organizational and professional roles with clear role requirements, gender roles are relatively salient (Eagly, 1987). Second, in the local church setting, jobs are highly sex segregated (Ngo et al., 2003). Because of sex segregation and the assignment of differential tasks for men and women, gender roles become important and even more relevant to job performance than do other social roles. Personal relative deprivation occurs when an individual feels disadvan- taged in his or her job situation relative to others in his or her own group. For a woman, this social comparison group is often comprised of other women (Crosby, 1982). Crosby (1982) suggested that because of job and occupa- tional segregation, women typically use other women as their social compar- ison group and consequently have lower expectations for work rewards than do men. Men will react more negatively to injustice than will women because (a) men have been socialized to derive satisfaction from outcomes obtained from competition; (b) men may be more likely to be concerned with fairness issues because procedures and outcomes generally favor them (Sweeney & McFarlin, 1997); and (c) in moral problem solving, men primarily employ a justice orientation characterized by considerations of fairness and equity (Gilligan, 1982). Thus, we expect that men will react more strongly to per- ceived distributive and procedural justice than will women. Hypothesis 6a: Gender will moderate the relationship between perceived distribu- tive justice and job satisfaction. Specifically, the more fair the reward, the higher men’s job satisfaction compared to women’s. Hypothesis 6b: Gender will moderate the relationship between perceived distribu- tive justice and organizational commitment. Specifically, the more fair the reward, the higher men’s organizational commitment compared to women’s. Hypothesis 7a: Gender will moderate the relationship between perceived proce- dural justice and job satisfaction. Specifically, the more fair the process, the higher men’s job satisfaction compared to women’s. Hypothesis 7b: Gender will moderate the relationship between perceived proce- dural justice and organizational commitment. Specifically, the more fair the process, the higher men’s organizational commitment compared to women’s. MEDIATING RELATIONSHIP Job satisfaction and organizational commitment may function as media- tors in our model because they account for the relationship between fairness and discrimination perceptions and an individual’s intention to leave the organization. We argue that unfairness or discrimination alone may not cause an individual to consider leaving the organization. However, when the unfairness or discrimination translates into dissatisfaction or low commit- Foley et al. / PERCEPTIONS OF DISCRIMINATION AND JUSTICE 431 ment, they take on significance through these work-related attitudes. In other words, job dissatisfaction and low organizational commitment intervene between perceptions and intentions to leave and account for why or how indi- viduals intend to leave. Therefore, although we have hypothesized that per- ceptions of unfairness and discrimination will affect an individual’s intention to leave the organization, the mechanism by which these variations in inten- tions to leave are produced is through job dissatisfaction and low organizational commitment. Hypothesis 8a: Job satisfaction mediates the effects of perceived gender discrimi- nation, distributive justice, and procedural justice on intentions to leave. Hypothesis 8b: Organizational commitment mediates the effects of perceived gender discrimination, distributive justice, and procedural justice on inten- tions to leave. METHOD SAMPLE AND PROCEDURE Our sample is comprised of Protestant clergy in Hong Kong. We chose clergy as our respondents for many reasons. First, gender inequity and dis- crimination at work has long been a concern in religious organizations (Chang, 2000; Nesbitt, 1997; Ngo & Wong, 2002). Partly because of reli- gious doctrines and traditions, women clergy have been disproportionately absent from positions of authority, and they face difficulties in being ac- cepted (Nesbitt, 1996). As female clergy confront more discrimination than their male colleagues, it is interesting to study how their job attitudes are affected by the perception of gender discrimination at work. Second, in re- cent research, justice evaluations are found to affect pay satisfaction among clergy (Younts & Mueller, 2001). Few studies, however, have examined other outcomes of organizational justice in the church setting. Third, clergy have been viewed as a “professional occupational labor market” character- ized by long-term career orientation (McDuff & Mueller, 2000). Compared to workers in the business sector, clergy tend to have longer job tenure and to care more about their long-term career prospects in the organization. Clergy are characterized by their professional service orientation, a “calling” that goes beyond self-interest toward the divine (McDuff & Mueller, 2000). A sense of calling reflects the public service ideal that is one of the primary criteria of a profession (Hatch, 1988). Using clergy as our sample helps us to understand more about how professional workers perceive fairness and 432 GROUP & ORGANIZATION MANAGEMENT discrimination at work and about how organizational conditions affect their perceptions. The data come from a survey of Protestant clergy conducted in Hong Kong in 2001. The target respondents were 2,600 pastors and preachers for local churches. All of the respondents were local Chinese. A Christian asso- ciation provided the names and mailing addresses for these clergy. Mailed to each potential respondent was a self-administered questionnaire along with a cover letter that explained the purpose of the survey (i.e., to understand the work situation and role expectation of clergy) and that invited them to partic- ipate on a voluntary basis. All respondents were assured of confidentiality and asked to return their completed questionnaire to a research center affili- ated with a local university. A follow-up call was made to remind the respon- dents to complete the questionnaire 3 to 4 weeks after the initial mailing. A total of 877 surveys were finally returned, representing a response rate of 33.7%. The questionnaires were administered in Chinese with some well- established scales developed in the West. Items for these scales were origi- nally developed in English and then translated into Chinese. The wording of some items was modified to fit the research setting. To ensure the quality of the translation, a back-translation was also done (Brislin, 1970). Among the respondents, 52.5% were male and 67.6% were married. The average work experience and organizational tenure were 9.5 and 5.6 years, respectively. Regarding their job positions, 21.7% were pastors and 64.0% were preachers. 27.1% of them (mostly pastors) reported that they were in charge of the church. Male and female clergy, however, reported holding dif- ferent job positions in the hierarchy. Of the male respondents, 157 (34.3%) and 217 (47.4%) were pastors and preachers, respectively. The figures were 32 (7.7%) and 341 (82.4%) for the female respondents. In fact, more men were granted ordination (to be pastors) than were women. Moreover, among those who are in charge of their church, 190 (80.5%) were male and 46 (19.5%) were female, which reflected that female clergy are less likely to be appointed or promoted to that position compared with their male colleagues. MEASURES Perceived gender discrimination. Four items, adopted from Sanchez and Brock (1996), were used to measure respondents’ perception of gender dis- crimination in the workplace. The original scale with 10 items was designed to measure perceived ethnic discrimination among Hispanic employees. We selected and modified four items from that scale to fit our research context. Coefficient alpha for this scale was 0.868. Foley et al. / PERCEPTIONS OF DISCRIMINATION AND JUSTICE 433 Distributive justice. Distributive justice was measured by four items tap- ping perceived fairness of reward that were modified from Goodman (1974) and from Tremblay and Roussel (2001). The perceived justice of rewards was broken down into justice based on efforts and time, based on internal equity (colleagues in the same organization), and based on external equity (workers in other organizations). This scale has a high alpha coefficient of 0.943. Procedural justice. Procedural justice was assessed with four items modi- fied from Balkin and Gomez-Mejia (1990) and from Parker, Baltes, and Christiansen (1997) to capture the perceived fairness of the procedures used to make personnel decisions and to determine work arrangements. These items focused mainly on respondents’ inputs into and degrees of involve- ment in the decision-making process. Coefficient alpha for this scale was 0.831. Job satisfaction. This variable was measured by a three-item scale devel- oped by Price and Mueller (1981). Coefficient alpha for this scale was 0.861. Organizational commitment. A short form of the affective organizational commitment scale developed by Allen and Meyer (1990) was employed. We changed the word “organization” to the word “church” in our scale items. This scale had an alpha coefficient alpha of 0.849. Intentions to leave. This variable was measured by a three-item scale developed by Cohen (1998) and based on Mobley, Griffin, Hand, and Meglino’s (1979) definition. The three items had an alpha coefficient of 0.855. The items and scales of the above measures are shown in the Appendix. Gender. Males were coded as 0, and females were coded as 1. Control variables. A review of previous studies on clergy’s job attitudes suggested three important variables to control for in the analysis, including church size, tenure with the current church, and job position. McDuff and Meuller (2002) pointed out that clergy who serve large churches tend to have a high level of job satisfaction and attachment to their current parish. In our study, church size refers to the size of congregation as measured with nine categories ranging from “less than 50 parishioners” to “more than 1000 parishioners.” We follow the works of McDuff (2001) and McDuff and Mueller (2000) to control for organizational tenure, which is often found to 434 GROUP & ORGANIZATION MANAGEMENT be a significant predictor of job satisfaction and organizational commitment. It is measured as the respondent’s total number of years working in the church. Lastly, ministerial position is related to work autonomy and author- ity in decision-making that affects work satisfaction (McDuff, 2001). In our study, job position is indicated by a dummy variable coded 1 if the respon- dent is the person who is in charge of the church and coded 0 if the respondent is not. STATISTICAL ANALYSES We employed hierarchical regression to test the hypotheses. Separate analyses were conducted for job satisfaction, organizational commitment, and intentions to leave. For the analysis of job satisfaction and organizational commitment, the control variables were entered in the regression model in step 1. Discrimination and justice perceptions were then entered as a block in step 2, followed by gender in step 3. In the last step, the three interaction terms (i.e., gender with discrimination, distributive justice, and procedural justice) were entered. Such a stepwise design was used to test the moderating effect of gender (Baron & Kenny, 1986). Our hypotheses were tested by examining the regression coefficients and the change in model R2 at each step. For moderator hypothesis testing, we employed a less stringent signifi- cance level (i.e., 0.1) because measurement error and shared variances make Type II errors likely. Significant interactions were plotted to show the exact moderating effect. For testing mediating relationships, we adopted the proce- dure suggested by Baron and Kenny (1986). We first regressed job satisfac- tion and organizational commitment, the two potential mediators, on the three independent variables (i.e., perceived gender discrimination, distribu- tive justice, and procedural justice). Then, we regressed intentions to leave on these independent variables. Finally, we regressed intentions to leave on both the independent variables and on the mediators. The mediation effects can be shown by the changes in the regression coefficients of the independent variables in different models. RESULTS Table 1 presents the means, standard deviations, and zero-order correla- tions among the study variables. Perceived gender discrimination was nega- tively correlated with distributive and procedural justice (r = –.27 and –.31, respectively). It also showed a negative correlation with job satisfaction (r = –.23) and organizational commitment (r = –.29) and a positive correlation Foley et al. / PERCEPTIONS OF DISCRIMINATION AND JUSTICE 435 with intentions to leave (r = .37). In addition, the correlation of distributive justice and procedural justice was strong (r = .58). These two variables were positively related to job satisfaction (r = .32 and .38, respectively) and orga- nizational commitment (r = .50 and .61, respectively), and both were nega- tively related to intentions to leave (r = –.35 and –.42, respectively). To test for common method variance and to help establish the convergent and discriminant validity of the major constructs in this study, we performed a confirmatory factor analysis using LISREL 8.30. All items for the six per- ceptual and attitudinal measures were included in the analysis. The results revealed that the six-factor model provides a good fit to the data, with a chi- square value of 808.03 (df = 174; p < .01). The root-mean-square error of approximation (RMSEA) was 0.064, whereas the goodness of fit index (GFI) and comparative fit index (CFI) were 0.92 and 0.95, respectively. All the indicators loaded exactly on their respective constructs. t-tests were conducted to show the gender differences in study variables. As shown in Table 2, male and female respondents were different in their perceptions of gender discrimination (t = –6.79, p < .001), with female clergy perceiving more gender discrimination in the workplace than did their male colleagues. Male respondents also reported a slightly higher level of distribu- tive and procedural justice (t = 2.11 and 2.70, p < .01 and p < .05, respec- tively) than did female respondents. Men were higher on organizational commitment (t = 3.05, p < .01) and lower on intentions to leave (t = –2.03, p < .05), but no significant difference was found between men and women in their level of job satisfaction. Tables 3 and 4 display the results of regression analyses on job satisfac- tion and organizational commitment, respectively. The direct effects of per- ceived gender discrimination, distributive justice, and procedural justice are evaluated in Model 2. First, perceived gender discrimination was negatively related to job satisfaction (β = –.07, p < .05) and organizational commitment (β = –.07, p < .05). This provides support for Hypotheses 1a and 1b. Addi- tionally, both distributive justice and procedural justice were significantly related to job satisfaction (β = .11, p < .01 and β = .28, p < .01, respectively) and organizational commitment (β = .19, p < .01 and β = .44, p < .01, respec- tively) in the predicted direction. Thus, Hypotheses 2a, 2b, 3a, and 3b gained empirical support. When gender was entered in Model 3, it did not account for a significant amount of variance for either outcome variable. Hypotheses 5a to 7b posit that gender will play a moderating role in the above relation- ships. To test these hypotheses, three interaction terms were included in Model 4, and they slightly increased the explained variance in job satisfac- tion (∆R2 = .01, p < .1) and organizational commitment (∆R2 = .01, p < .05). 436 GROUP & ORGANIZATION MANAGEMENT 437 T A B L E 1 M ea n s, S ta n d ar d D ev ia ti on s an d C or re la ti on s A m on g S tu d y V ar ia b le s V a ri a b le M S D 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 1 0 1. G en de r (f em al e = 1 ) 0. 47 0. 50 2. O rg an iz at io na l te nu re 5. 57 4. 99 –0 .1 1* * 3. Jo b po si ti on 0. 27 0. 44 –0 .3 4* * 0. 28 ** 4. C hu rc h si ze 3. 94 2. 34 0. 03 0. 02 –0 .2 3* * 5. P er ce iv ed g en de r di sc ri m in at io n 2. 65 1. 09 0. 22 ** –0 .0 9* –0 .1 5* * –0 .0 8* 6. D is tr ib ut iv e ju st ic e 4. 49 1. 12 –0 .0 7* 0. 12 ** 0. 12 ** 0. 02 –0 .2 7* * 7. P ro ce du ra l ju st ic e 4. 43 0. 99 –0 .0 9* 0. 14 ** 0. 19 ** –0 .1 1* * –0 .3 1* * 0. 58 ** 8. Jo b sa ti sf ac ti on 4. 75 0. 80 –0 .0 5 0. 16 ** 0. 18 ** 0. 05 –0 .2 3* * 0. 32 ** 0. 38 ** 9. O rg an iz at io na l co m m it m en t 4. 72 1. 02 –0 .1 0* * 0. 29 ** 0. 21 ** –0 .0 1 –0 .2 9* * 0. 50 ** 0. 61 ** 0. 56 ** 10 . In te nt io ns t o le av e 2. 18 1. 09 0. 07 * –0 .1 1* * –0 .1 6* * –0 .0 1 0. 37 ** –0 .3 5* * –0 .4 2* * –0 .4 6* * –0 .5 7* * N O T E : A ll t w o- ta il ed t es ts . *p < .0 5. * *p < .0 1. The interaction of gender with perceived gender discrimination was signifi- cant for organizational commitment (β = –.24, p < .01) but not for job satis- faction. In other words, Hypothesis 5b was supported, and Hypothesis 5a was not supported. Based on the procedure suggested by Holmbeck (1997) 438 GROUP & ORGANIZATION MANAGEMENT TABLE 2 Gender Differences in Study Variables Variable x for males x for females t-value Organizational tenure 6.09 4.97 3.25** Job position 0.41 0.11 10.71** Church size 3.89 4.01 –0.73 Perceived gender discrimination 2.42 2.91 –6.79** Distributive justice 4.57 4.41 2.11* Procedural justice 4.51 4.33 2.70** Job satisfaction 4.78 4.70 1.39 Organizational commitment 4.81 4.60 3.05** Intentions to leave 2.11 2.26 –2.03* NOTE: n range from 836 to 872. *p < .05. **p < .01. TABLE 3 Regression Analysis on Job Satisfaction Predictor Model 1 Model 2 Model 3 Model 4 Organizational tenure 0.11** 0.07* 0.07* 0.07* Job position 0.16** 0.09** 0.11** 0.11** Church size 0.08* 0.09** 0.09** 0.09** Perceived gender discrimination –0.07* –0.08* –0.13* Distributive justice 0.11** 0.11** 0.17** Procedural justice 0.28** 0.28** 0.27** Gender (female = 1) 0.06† 0.21 Gender x perceived 0.11 gender discrimination Gender x distributive justice –0.28† Gender x procedural justice 0.03 R 2 0.05** 0.19** 0.19** 0.20** F-statistic 13.80 31.74 27.72 20.12 ∆ R2 0.14** 0.01† 0.01† F-statistic 47.34 3.10 2.13 NOTE: n = 822. Standardized regression coefficients are reported. † p < .1. *p < .05. **p < .01. for a dichotomous moderator, we plotted the interaction effect. As shown in Figure 2, the effect of perceived gender discrimination on organizational commitment was stronger for women than for men. It is also worthy to note that the interaction of gender with distributive justice was significant for job satisfaction (β = –.28, p < .1) but not for organizational commitment. Thus, Hypothesis 6a was supported, and Hypothesis 6b was not supported. Figure 3 reveals that distributive justice was associated with lower job satisfaction for men than for women. Since the interaction of gender with procedural justice was not significant for either outcome variable, Hypotheses 7a and 7b were not supported by the data. The results of regression analysis for intentions to leave are shown in Table 5. Model 1 is the baseline model that includes gender and the control variables. In Model 2, when perceived gender discrimination and the two jus- tice variables were entered, they raised the explained variance by 22%. Spe- cifically, it was found that perceived gender discrimination (β = .25, p < .01) had a positive effect, whereas distributive justice (β = –.11, p < .01) and pro- cedural justice (β = –.27, p < .01) had a negative effect on intentions to leave. Thus, support was found for Hypotheses 4a, 4b, and 4c. However, in Model Foley et al. / PERCEPTIONS OF DISCRIMINATION AND JUSTICE 439 TABLE 4 Regression Analysis on Organizational Commitment Predictor Model 1 Model 2 Model 3 Model 4 Organizational tenure 0.25** 0.19** 0.19** 0.19** Job position 0.14** 0.05 0.05 0.05† Church size 0.02 0.04 0.04 0.04 Perceived gender discrimination –0.07* –0.07* 0.02 Distributive justice 0.19** 0.19** 0.23** Procedural justice 0.44** 0.44** 0.44** Gender (female = 1) 0.01 0.39* Gender x perceived –0.24** gender discrimination Gender x distributive justice –0.16 Gender x procedural justice –0.03 R 2 0.10** 0.44** 0.44** 0.45** F-statistic 31.70 107.97 92.44 66.01 ∆ R2 0.34** 0.00 0.01* F-statistic 165.18 0.03 2.87 NOTE: n = 823. Standardized regression coefficients are reported. † p < .1. *p < .05. **p < .01. 440 GROUP & ORGANIZATION MANAGEMENT 4 4.5 5 Low High Perceived Gender Discrimination O rg a n iz a ti o n a l C o m m it m e n t Males Females Males Females Figure 2: Moderating Effect of Gender on the Relationship Between Perceived Gender Discrimination and Organizational Commitment 4 4.5 5 Low High Distributive Justice J o b S a ti s fa c ti o n Males Females Figure 3: Moderating Effect of Gender on the Relationship Between Distributive Justice and Job Satisfaction 3, the interaction terms of gender with perceived gender discrimination, dis- tributive justice, and procedural justice were insignificant. Hypotheses 8a and 8b, stating that job satisfaction and organizational commitment mediate the effects of gender discrimination and distributive and procedural justice on intentions to leave, were tested according to Baron and Kenny’s (1986) procedure. As shown in Models 1, 2, and 3 in Table 6, the three predictors significantly affected job satisfaction and organizational commitment (i.e., the two hypothesized mediators) and intentions to leave in the predicted direction. In Model 4, when both the mediators and independ- ent variables are included, the significant effects of distributive justice and procedural justice in the previous model disappeared. Taking these findings together, both Hypotheses 8a and 8b were supported in that job satisfaction and organizational commitment fully mediated the effects of justice percep- tions on intentions to leave. However, the effect of perceived gender discrim- ination remained significant in Model 4. This variable seems to have a strong direct effect on intentions to leave and not through job satisfaction and organizational commitment. Foley et al. / PERCEPTIONS OF DISCRIMINATION AND JUSTICE 441 TABLE 5 Regression Analysis on Intentions to Leave Predictor Model 1 Model 2 Model 3 Organizational tenure –0.06† –0.02 –0.02 Job position –0.16** –0.09* –0.08* Church size –0.04 –0.03 –0.03 Gender (female = 1) 0.01 –0.05 –0.14 Perceived gender discrimination 0.25** 0.25** Distributive justice –0.11** –0.14** Procedural justice –0.27** –0.26** Gender x perceived gender discrimination –0.00 Gender x distributive justice –0.04 Gender x procedural justice 0.13 R 2 0.03** 0.26** 0.26** F-statistic 7.10 40.04 28.04 ∆ R2 0.22** 0.00 F-statistic 81.17 0.28 NOTE: n = 821. Standardized regression coefficients are reported. † p < .1. *p < .05. **p < .01. DISCUSSION In the present study, perceived injustice and gender discrimination were significantly related to job dissatisfaction, low organizational commitment, and greater intentions to leave the organization. Additionally, we found that women perceived higher levels of gender discrimination than did men, and for women, perceptions of gender discrimination were associated with lower organizational commitment but not with job satisfaction. This suggests that women may more strongly attribute gender discrimination to the organiza- tion than do men. Thus, their commitment to the organization is adversely affected as a result. Women’s satisfaction with their jobs, which may be seen as separate from the organization, is not particularly affected by their per- ception of gender discrimination. The other significant moderating relationship we found was between dis- tributive justice and job satisfaction, which was stronger for men than for women. As shown in Table 2, women reported a lower level of perceived procedural and distributive justice perceptions than did men, and both differ- ences were statistically significant. However, the effects of distributive and procedural justice were about the same for both sexes, supporting Fields et al.’s (2000) conclusion that women in Hong Kong may expect equal treat- ment with men in recognition and rewards, and hence they respond similarly to men. For female and male clergy, their responses to justice may be similar because they are highly educated and share the same religious values. 442 GROUP & ORGANIZATION MANAGEMENT TABLE 6 Testing Mediating Effects of Job Satisfaction and Organizational Commitment Model 1: Model 2: Model 3: Model 4: Job Organizational Intentions Intentions Predictor Satisfaction Commitment to Leave to Leave Perceived gender discrimination –0.10** –0.08** 0.25** 0.20** Distributive justice 0.13** 0.20** –0.12** –0.02 Procedural justice 0.27** 0.46** –0.27** –0.05 Job satisfaction –0.18** Organizational commitment –0.39** Adjusted R2 0.17 0.40 0.25 0.40 F-statistic 58.39** 195.49** 95.65** 117.03** n 864 865 863 863 NOTE: Standardized regression coefficients are reported. *p < .05. **p < .01. Furthermore, we found a relationship between perceived distributive and procedural justice and intentions to leave the organization through the medi- ating effects of job satisfaction and organizational commitment. Unfair pro- cedures and outcomes alone may not be enough to result in individuals’ intentions to quit their present job. Our findings revealed that job satisfaction and organizational commitment fully mediated the relationships between justice perceptions and intentions to leave. This confirms the importance of satisfaction and commitment as intervening variables in models of turnover intentions (Williams & Hazer, 1986). We were surprised to find that the relationship between gender discrimi- nation and intentions to leave the organization was not mediated by job satis- faction and organizational commitment, suggesting that gender discrimina- tion alone is enough to affect individuals’ leave intentions. Individuals seem to form leave intentions in part by directly considering the gender discrimi- nation experienced in their organization. IMPLICATIONS FOR THEORY By measuring both discrimination and justice perceptions, researchers can better understand how organizational conditions and processes affect job satisfaction and organizational commitment and how these work-related atti- tudes drive intentions to leave. The present study makes several contribu- tions to the literature. First, it examines discrimination from the point of view of those who may actually be experiencing discrimination. Thus, it offers insight into the reactions and work-related outcomes of the victims of dis- crimination. Second, our study establishes a theoretical and empirical link, not often recognized in the current literature, between the gender discrim- ination literature and justice theory. Third, our study answers Barak, Cherin, and Berkman’s (1998) call for future research examining employees’ per- ceptions of discrimination and the impact on their job attitudes. Fourth, Hofstede’s (1980, 2001) masculinity dimension may help in predicting gen- der differences in individuals’ perceived justice and discrimination in the workplace. Last, we address Sweeney and McFarlin’s (1997) view that much more needs to be done to identify factors or conditions that affect the moder- ating role that gender has on justice/outcome relationships. As we use clergy as our sample, the present study enables us to understand more about gender differences in a professional setting. IMPLICATIONS FOR PRACTICE Our findings have practical implications for understanding the moder- ating effect of gender on the perception-intention relationships we tested. Foley et al. / PERCEPTIONS OF DISCRIMINATION AND JUSTICE 443 Perceptions of unfair organizational rewards have a more negative effect on men’s job satisfaction than on women’s job satisfaction. This would suggest to managers that the fairness of rewards is particularly important to men and that managers should endeavor to be perceived as fair when making reward allocations to minimize the adverse impact on job satisfaction. Continued research on the managerial practices that influence fairness perceptions will contribute to the design and implementation of fair allocative procedures and outcomes. Managers need to realize that decreasing employees’ perceptions of unfairness and discrimination is as important to employee retention as increasing job satisfaction and organizational commitment. The direct effect of gender discrimination on intentions to leave also has practical implications. The perception of gender discrimination in the work- place directly affects employees’ intentions to leave regardless of how satis- fied they are in their job or how committed they may be to the organization. Gender discrimination creates an overall negative work environment for all employees (Ensher et al., 2001); thus, individuals who perceive gender dis- crimination may be more likely to consider leaving the organization. Our results should alert managers to the negative consequences of employees’ attributing differences in treatment to their gender. Management decisions and communications with employees should be carefully shaped to prevent perceptions of differential treatment based on gender. LIMITATIONS AND DIRECTIONS FOR FUTURE RESEARCH Some methodological limitations of our study should be acknowledged. First, the potential for social desirability bias influencing responses was pres- ent because of the sensitive nature of the questions. This limitation was addressed in part by the guaranteed confidentiality of responses. Second, all of the variables were assessed by self-report measures, raising the possibility of common-methods bias. Third, the study was cross-sectional and did not capture trends within organizations, but causal relationships were inferred. One must be sure to note that causal inferences made from cross-sectional designs are never more than inferences (Moorman, 1991). Fourth, the view- point of the decision-makers, which may have shed further light on the per- ceptions of fairness and discrimination, was not assessed. Last, the depen- dent variables consisted of attitudes rather than behaviors. The behavioral consequences of justice and discrimination perceptions also need to be examined to understand the full ramifications of the gender differences in work-related attitudes. In addition, three potential limitations to the generalizability of this theo- retical perspective deserve comment. One issue concerns whether and to 444 GROUP & ORGANIZATION MANAGEMENT what extent the theoretical framework developed here generalizes across dif- ferent types of professions. We believe that our results generalize to other workers in helping professions (e.g., social workers) as well as to other work- ers in the non-profit sector because they face similar work conditions and practices as clergy. Future research is needed to cross-validate the current model using other professional employees as well as different nationalities and denominations. A second issue is whether and to what extent the theo- retical framework developed here generalizes across different types of out- comes (including both positive and negative ones) or to outcomes less ame- nable to social comparison. Third, the generalizability of these findings may extend only to those countries that are high on the masculinity dimension (e.g., the United States, Japan, Mexico, Germany, and Austria) rather than low-masculinity countries (e.g., Sweden, Norway, the Netherlands, Den- mark, and Finland). Future research is needed to cross-validate the current model using other professional employees, different nationalities, and social groups other than male and female. A longitudinal research design may better assess individu- als’ intentions to leave or remain with an organization (Farkas & Tetrick, 1989). Therefore, future research that can track a cohort of employees in an organization is needed. In conclusion, this study broadens our understanding of the influence of perceived (in)justice and gender discrimination on job attitudes for male and female professional workers. APPENDIX A six-point Likert-type scale format (1 = Strongly Disagree; 6 = Strongly Agree) was used to measure employees’ perceptions and job attitudes in this study. Perceived Gender Discrimination (α = .868) 1. At work, I sometimes feel that my gender is a limitation. 2. My gender has a negative influence on my career advancement. 3. At work, many people have sex stereotypes and treat me as if they were true. 4. At work, I feel that others exclude me from their activities because of my gender. Distributive Justice (α = .943) 1. Compared with my effort and time I put, I receive reasonable reward. 2. Compared with my colleagues, I receive reasonable reward. 3. Compared with workers in other churches, I receive reasonable reward. 4. I get the reward that I deserve. Foley et al. / PERCEPTIONS OF DISCRIMINATION AND JUSTICE 445 Procedural Justice (α = .831) 1. My church tries to understand the view of workers on pay and work arrange- ments through various channels. 2. Workers are involved in making decisions that are related to their work. 3. Workers can express their opinions concerning their job assignment. 4. There is sufficient visibility on personnel decisions such as promotion and pay raise. Job satisfaction (α = .861) 1. I find real enjoyment in my job. 2. Most days I am enthusiastic about my job. 3. Overall speaking, I feel well satisfied with my job. Organizational Commitment (α = .849) 1. I would be very happy to spend the rest of my career with this church. 2. I really feel as if this church’s problems are my own. 3. I feel a strong sense of belonging to my church. Intentions to Leave (α = .855) 1. I think a lot about quitting my job. 2. I am actively searching for an alternative to my present job. 3. As soon as it is possible, I will leave the church. NOTE 1. In our study, gender is considered as the moderator. According to Baron and Kenny (1986), a moderator is a qualitative or quantitative variable that affects the direction and/or strength of the relation between an independent variable and a dependent variable. On the other hand, a mediator is a variable that accounts for the relation between the independent and the dependent variable. Whereas moderator variables specify when certain effects will hold, media- tors speak to how or why such effects occur. In our study, job satisfaction and organizational commitment are considered the two mediators between perceived gender discrimination, distrib- utive justice, procedural justice, and intentions to leave. REFERENCES Adams, J. S. (1965). Inequality in social exchange. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in experi- mental social psychology (pp. 267-299). New York: Academic Press. 446 GROUP & ORGANIZATION MANAGEMENT Allen, N. J., & Meyer, J. P. (1990). The measurement and antecedents of affective, continu- ance, and normative commitment to the organization. Journal of Occupational Psychology, 63, 1-18. Ashforth, B. E., & Mael, F. (1989). Social identity theory and the organization. Academy of Man- agement Review, 14, 20-39. Balkin, D., & Gomez-Mejia, L. (1990). Matching compensation and organizational strategies. Strategic Management Journal, 11, 153-169. Balser, D. B. (2002). Agency in organizational inequality: Organizational behavior and individ- ual perceptions of discrimination. Work and Occupations, 29, 137-165. Barak, M. E. M., Cherin, D. A., & Berkman, S. (1998). Organizational and personal dimensions in diversity climate: Ethnic and gender differences in employee perceptions. Journal of Applied Behavioral Science, 34, 82-104. Baron, R. M., & Kenny, D. A. (1986). The moderator-mediator variable distinction in social psy- chological research: Conceptual, strategic, and statistical considerations. Journal of Person- ality and Social Psychology, 51, 1173-1182. Bock, E. W. (1967). The female clergy: A case of professional marginality. American Journal of Sociology, 72, 531-539. Bond, M. H., & Hwang, K. K. (1986). The social psychology of the Chinese people. In M. H. Bond (Ed.), The Psychology of the Chinese People (pp. 213-266). Hong Kong: Oxford Uni- versity Press. Brislin, R. W. (1970). Back-translation for cross-cultural research. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology, 1, 185-216. Brockner, J., & Adsit, L. (1986). The moderating impact of sex on the equity-satisfaction rela- tionship: A field study. Journal of Applied Psychology, 71, 585-590. Capozza, D., & Brown, R. (Eds.) (2000). Social identity processes. London: Sage. Chang, P. M. Y. (2000). The effects of organizational variation in the employment relationship on gender discrimination in denominational labor markets. In H. Z. Lopata & K. D. Henson (Eds.), Current research on occupations and professions: Unusual occupations (Vol. 11, pp. 213-240). Stamford, CT: JAI. Cohen, A. (1998). An examination of the relationship between work commitment and work out- comes among hospital nurses. Scandinavian Journal of Management, 14, 1-17. Cohen-Charash, Y., & Spector, P. E. (2001). The role of justice in organizations: A meta- analysis. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 86, 278-321. Crosby, F. J. (1982). Relative deprivation and working women. New York: Oxford University Press. DeWitt, R. L., Trevino, L. K., & Mollica, K. A. (1998). The influence of eligibility on employ- ees’ reactions to voluntary workforce reductions. Journal of Management, 24, 593-613. Eagly, A. H. (1987). Sex differences in social behavior: A social-role interpretation. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. Ensher, E. A., Grant-Vallone, E. J., & Donalson, S. I. (2001). Effects of perceived discrimination on job satisfaction, organizational commitment, organizational citizenship behavior, and grievances. Human Resource Development Quarterly, 12, 53-72. Farkas, A. J., & Tetrick, L. E. (1989). A three-wave longitudinal analysis of the causal ordering of satisfaction and commitment on turnover decisions. Journal of Applied Psychology, 74, 855-868. Fields, D., Pang, M., & Chiu, C. (2000). A comparative field study of the effects of distributive and procedural justice in Hong Kong. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 21, 547-562. Foley, S., Kidder, D. L., & Powell, G. N. (2002). The perceived glass ceiling and justice percep- tions: An investigation of Hispanic law associates. Journal of Management, 28, 471-496. Foley et al. / PERCEPTIONS OF DISCRIMINATION AND JUSTICE 447 Folger, R., & Cropanzano, R. (1998). Organizational justice and human resource management. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Gilligan, C. (1982). In a different voice: Psychological theory and women’s development. Cam- bridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Goodman, P. S. (1974). An examination of referents used in the evaluation of pay. Organiza- tional Behavior and Human Performance, 12, 170-195. Greenberg, J. (1986). Organizational performance appraisal procedures: What makes them fair? In R. J. Lewicki, B. H. Sheppard, & M. H. Bazerman (Eds.), Research on negotiations in organizations (Vol. 1, pp. 25-41). Greenwich, CT: JAI. Greenberg, J. (1990). Organizational justice: Yesterday, today, and tomorrow. Journal of Man- agement, 16, 399-432. Gutek, B. A., Cohen, A. G., & Tsui, A. (1996). Reactions to perceived discrimination. Human Relations, 49, 791-813. Hatch, N. O. (1988). The professions in American history. Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame Univer- sity Press. Hofstede, G. (1980). Culture’s consequences: International differences in work-related values. London: Sage. Hofstede, G. (1993). Cultural constraints in management theories. Academy of Management Executive, 7, 81-94. Hofstede, G. (2001). Culture’s consequences: Comparing values, behaviors, institutions and organizations across nations. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Holmbeck, G. N. (1997). Toward terminological, conceptual, and statistical clarity in the study of mediators and moderators: Examples from the child-clinical and pediatric psychology lit- eratures. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 65, 599-610. Kim, W. C., & Mauborgne, R. (1998). Procedural justice, strategic decision making, and the knowledge economy. Strategic Management Journal, 19, 323-338. Lee, C., & Farh, J. L. (1999). The effects of gender in organizational justice perception. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 20, 133-143. Leventhal, G. S. (1980). What should be done with equity theory? New approaches to the study of fairness in social relationships. In K. J. Gergen, M. S. Greenberg, & R. H. Willis (Eds.), Social exchange: Advances in theory and research (pp. 27-55). New York: Plenum. Major, B. (1994). From social inequality to personal entitlement: The role of social comparisons, legitimacy appraisals, and group membership. In M. P. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in experimen- tal social psychology (Vol. 26, pp. 293-356). San Diego, CA: Academic Press. McDuff, E. M. (2001). The gender paradox in work satisfaction and the protestant clergy. Sociol- ogy of Religion, 62, 1-21. McDuff, E. M., & Mueller, C. W. (2000). The ministry as an occupational labor market. Work and Occupations, 27, 89-116. McDuff, E. M., & Mueller, C. W. (2002). Gender differences in the professional orientations of protestant clergy. Sociological Forum, 17, 465-491. Mobley, W. H., Griffin, R. W., Hand, H. H., & Meglino, B. M. (1979). Review and conceptual analysis of the employee turnover process. Psychological Bulletin, 86, 493-522. Moorman, R. H. (1991). Relationship between organizational justice and organizational citizen- ship behaviors: Do fairness perceptions influence employee citizenship? Journal of Applied Psychology, 76, 845-855. Morrison, A. M., White, R. P., & Van Velsor, E. (1987). Breaking the glass ceiling: Can women reach the top of America’s largest corporations? Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley. Nesbitt, P. D. (1996). Women Clergy. In P. J. Dubeck & K. Borman (Eds.), Women and work: A handbook (pp. 181-184). New York: Garland Publishing. 448 GROUP & ORGANIZATION MANAGEMENT Nesbitt, P. D. (1997). Feminization of the clergy in America: Occupational and organizational perspectives. New York: Oxford University Press. Ngo, H. Y., Foley, S., Wong, A., & Loi, R. (2003). Who gets more of the pie? Predictors of per- ceived gender inequity at work. Journal of Business Ethics, 45, 227-241. Ngo, H. Y., Tang, C., & Au, W. (2002). Behavioural responses to employment discrimination: A study of Hong Kong workers. International Journal of Human Resource Management, 13, 1206-1223. Ngo, H. Y., & Wong, W. C. (2002). A study on work conditions of protestant clergy in Hong Kong: A brief report. Hong Kong: Hong Kong Christian Council. Northcraft, G., & Gutek, B. A. (1993). Discrimination against women in management: Going, going, gone? or going, but never gone? In E. Fagenson (Ed.), Women in management: Trends, issues, and challenges in managerial diversity (pp. 219-245). Newbury Park, CA: Sage. Parker, C. P., Baltes, B. B., & Christiansen, N. D. (1997). Support for affirmative action, justice perceptions, and work attitudes: A study of gender and racial-ethnic group differences. Jour- nal of Applied Psychology, 82, 376-389. Price, J. L., & Mueller, C. W. (1981). Professional turnover: The case of nurses. New York: Spectrum. Primeaux, P., Karri, R., & Caldwell, C. (2003). Cultural insights to justice: A theoretical per- spective through a subjective lens. Journal of Business Ethics, 46, 187-199. Randall, M. L., Cropanzano, R., Bormann, C. A., & Birjulin, A. (1999). Organizational politics and organizational support as predictors of work attitudes, job performance, and organiza- tional citizenship behavior. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 20, 159-174. Randall, C. S., & Mueller, C. W. (1995). Extensions of justice theory: Justice evaluations and employee’s reactions in a natural setting. Social Psychology Quarterly, 58, 178-194. Rosin, H. M., & Korabik, K. (1991). Workplace variables, affective responses, and intention to leave among women managers. Journal of Occupational Psychology, 64, 317-330. Sanchez, J. I., & Brock, P. (1996). Outcomes of perceived discrimination among Hispanic employees: Is diversity management a luxury or a necessity? Academy of Management Jour- nal, 39, 704-719. Schmitt, M. T., Ellemers, N., & Branscombe, N. R. (2003). Perceiving and responding to gender discrimination at work. In S. A. Haslam, D. Van Knippenberg, M. Platow, & N. Ellemers (Eds.), Social identity at work: Developing theory for organizational practice (pp. 277-292). Philadelphia: Psychology Press. Schneider, C. J., & Schneider, D. (1997). In their own right: The history of American clergy- women. New York: Crossroad. Skarlicki, D. P., & Folger, R. (1997). Retaliation in the workplace: The roles of distributive, pro- cedural, and interactional justice. Journal of Applied Psychology, 82, 434-443. Stroh, L. K., Brett, J. M., & Reilly, A. H. (1996). Family structure, glass ceiling, and traditional explanations for the differential rate of turnover of female and male managers. Journal of Vocational Behavior, 49, 99-118. Sweeney, P. D., & McFarlin, D. B. (1997). Process and outcome: Gender differences in the assessment of justice. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 18, 83-98. Tajfel, H., & Turner, J. C. (1986). The social identity theory of intergroup behavior. In S. Worchel & W. G. Austin (Eds.), Psychology of intergroup relations (2nd ed., pp. 7-24). Chicago: Nelson-Hall. Tremblay, M., & Roussel, P. (2001). Modelling the role of organizational justice: Effects on sat- isfaction and unionization propensity of Canadian managers. International Journal of Human Resource Management, 12, 717-737. Foley et al. / PERCEPTIONS OF DISCRIMINATION AND JUSTICE 449 Trentham, S., & Larwood, L. (1998). Gender discrimination and the workplace: An examination of rational bias theory. Sex Roles, 38, 1-28. Vogel, D. L., Wester, S. R., Heesacker, M., & Madon, S. (2003). Confirming sex stereotypes: A social role perspective. Sex Roles, 48, 519-528. Wharton, A. S. (1992). The social construction of gender and race in organizations: A social identity and group mobilization perspective. In P. T. Tolbert & S. B. Bacharach (Eds.), Research in the sociology of organizations (Vol. 10, pp. 55-84). Greenwich, CT: JAI. Williams, L. J., & Hazer, J. T. (1986). Antecedents and consequences of satisfaction and com- mitment in turnover models: A reanalysis using latent variable structural equation methods. Journal of Applied Psychology, 71, 219-231. Younts, C. W., & Mueller, C. W. (2001). Justice processes: Specifying the mediating role of per- ceptions of distributive justice. American Sociological Review, 66, 125-145. Sharon Foley is an assistant professor of management in the LeBow College of Business at Drexel University, Philadelphia, PA. She has a Ph.D. from the University of Connecti- cut, and her research interests include diversity in the workplace and the work-family interface. Ngo Hang-yue is a professor in the Department of Management at the Chinese Univer- sity of Hong Kong. He obtained his Ph.D. from the University of Chicago. His current research interests include gender and employment, human resource management, and labor issues in China. Angela Wong is an associate professor in the Department of Modern Languages and Intercultural Studies at the Chinese University of Hong Kong. She is also a member of the Committee on Gender Studies and the Gender Research Centre of the same University. 450 GROUP & ORGANIZATION MANAGEMENT work_fozbgqb2x5czjje43xd5vz7j6i ---- S2053447718000441jra 158..173 The Differend of Justice: Violence and Redemption in Dworkin’s Justice for Hedgehogs ABSTRACT: This article uses Ronald Dworkin’s argument for the unity of value to explore the redemptive core of modern legal order. Dworkin establishes a formal unity: all legal claims reside within a linked framework of moral justification. However, Jean-Francois Lyotard’s concept of the differend exposes a lingering gap. Arguments within a moral universe do inevitably converge, but such unity is only possible due to the formative violence enacted by such orders. Dworkin hopes to provide the definitive statement against moral subjectivity, but in its purest form, he proves precisely the opposite. The lesson to draw from Dworkin’s work is that ‘justice’ is ultimately only the means by which political orders categorize and thereby sustain their own formative acts of exclusion under the guise of offering their redemption. KEYWORDS: justice, interpretation, moral reason, Dworkin, Lyotard, Gadamer In Justice for Hedgehogs, the final major work of his long career, Ronald Dworkin recalls that that old line of poetry, made famous by Isaiah Berlin: ‘the fox knows many things, but the hedgehog knows one big thing’ (Berlin : ). Dworkin’s goal: nothing less than the integration of ‘theories of truth, language, and metaphysics with and into the more familiar realms of value’ (Dworkin : ). In this formulation, every seeming distinction between moral claims is facile, as are distinctions between objects of interpretation and the interpreting subject. The apparent contradictions are simply a product of thinking like a fox. Once framed correctly, the hedgehog’s perspective will reveal a deeper unity and coherence. This article takes Dworkin’s argument as an invitation to explore the possibilities and limits of justice. Hedgehogs is important, I argue, not because it fully succeeds, but rather due to the nature of its failure. Dworkin does correctly describe an underlying unity of political, moral, and legal thought. However, this unity remains incomplete. And, crucially, its incompleteness cannot be detached from its scope. As Dworkin successfully proves, the trans-historical unity of value is not unique to his approach but instead is present in every instance and formulation of justice. His failures, therefore, expose the failures of justice as such. But what exactly is the nature of this failure? Though he does not characterize it in these terms, I argue that Dworkin’s ‘unity’ is best understood as a form of fidelity to the redemptive potential of shared meaning, which regards every form of exclusion as an invitation to recuperation. This orientation toward redemption is the beating Journal of the American Philosophical Association () – © American Philosophical Association DOI:./apa.. Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2018.44 https://www.cambridge.org/core heart of modernity’s secular orientation—a world without theological certainty, where faith must be transferred to the architecture of justice (Schmitt ). But for all that ‘justice as redemption’ is ubiquitous, it is rarely acknowledged as such. And this clarifies the importance of Dworkin’s work. By recentering our theoretical gaze on the process of justification, and by challenging any attempt to fragment our perspective, he provides a crucial vantage point for describing and critiquing the redemptive impulse. The terms of this argument are presented in two stages. The first is a process of immanent critique, in which Dworkin’s work is compared to the hermeneutics of Hans-Georg Gadamer. While these approaches are by no means identical— indeed, Dworkin’s late career work might be read as a repudiation of his earlier dalliance with Gadamer—beneath the surface, they each embody a similar faith in the potential for integration. That is, they presume that interpretive gaps are not only amenable to negotiation, but that such negotiation is the heart of meaningful political engagement. The symmetry at this level may be most usefully understood as a shared commitment to the idea of interpretation as a technique of redemption, where justice is not defined by the elimination of exclusion but rather by the continuous practice of redeeming exclusions by fitting them into a larger scheme of justification. In Dworkin’s case, this occurs through a process of persistent self-evaluation—which regards each supposed gap as an invitation to recalibrate the linked structure of normative obligation. Gadamer rejects this integrative objective—arguing for the need to preserve interpretive gaps as the necessary terrain on which understanding may be sought. These approaches differ in both goal and method, but converge in one crucial way: for each, justice is not a result to be achieved but rather a process of continual transition—conducted in the name of a redemptive principle that exceeds material achievement. The second stage of the argument takes this immanent critique as an invitation to reflect on the limitations of justice as redemption as a form of political practice. Here, I draw on Jean-François Lyotard’s concept of the differend to illustrate the durability of a formative violence, which includes both the conceptual exclusion of meaning-making as well as the material exclusion of law-making. The differend of justice is the inextinguishable violence that resides within the structures of every moral order—which can neither be acknowledged nor resolved. It is the point of exception, which cannot even be characterized as injustice, because it exceeds the concept of justice itself. Dworkin’s own argument for the unity of moral thought provides the necessary bridge for this claim. Tracing the flows of normativity backward exposes the indelible status of redemption at the heart of every justice claim. By stripping away all the accouterments of normativity, Dworkin hopes to restore its universal potential. All political claims, he argues, are ultimately normative in nature, and therefore imply the potential to stitch together that which appears fractured. By establishing the universality of this premise, Dworkin seeks to divide the world between justice and injustice. But in this separation the excluded third is never fully resolved. It lingers on, as the foundational violence upon which its order is sustained, and against which the redemptive potential of justice is delineated. Because it cannot be incorporated, such violence is neither ‘just’ nor ‘unjust;’ it simply is. T H E D I F F E R E N D O F J U S T I C E  Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core Dworkin deserves credit and attention for scaling the heights of theoretical inquiry. He has climbed to the highest peak of justice. Unfortunately, it is only from this vantage point that its tensions are revealed to be terminally irresolvable. I. The Unity of Value: Interpretation for Hedgehogs Justice for Hedgehogs is framed as a reformulation of ‘law as integrity’, Dworkin’s prior model of legal interpretation. That approach posited an active role for the legal thinker: to make law ‘the best that it can be’ (Dworkin : ). In contrast with the ‘plain facts’ view of law that imagines a legal order to exist in an objective sense (See Hart ), Dworkin argues that interpretation is a constructive practice that necessarily helps to generate the concept being interpreted. Given these constraints, any decision about what the law is must also be a decision about what the law ought to mean. But, simultaneously, the normative value of law cannot be disentangled from its historical location. That is: what the law ought to be depends on its interpretive community (Dworkin : –). A judge should interpret legal practices in the best light, but this is always dependent on existent communal interpretive practices that render the concept meaningful. In Justice for Hedgehogs, Dworkin criticizes this old approach. Law as integrity, he now argues, suffered from a critical lacuna. As a theory of legal interpretation, it could instruct a judge how to act with integrity but it lacked the scope needed to justify why a judge should adopt this method in the first place. In effect, its interpretive mode required an act of faith in the principle that law deserves to be treated with integrity. This means its entire apparatus was parasitic on a prior, external choice to affirm a ‘larger integrated network of political value’ that enframes the entire structure of legal reason (Dworkin : ; see also Prǐbáň : –). Law as integrity, in this way, smuggled the notion of fidelity to law into the process of interpreting it. The realization that law as integrity presumed a truth it lacked the capacity to justify leads him to broaden his perspective. In doing so, he concludes that all interpretation follows this same structure—any moral statement necessarily contains an implicit self-affirming principle that statements can in fact be valid (Dworkin : ). Furthermore, this principle extends to ‘nonmoral’ statements as well. After all, stating the absence of an obligation is simply a reconfigured moral judgment, insofar as it asserts the truth of nonobligation (Dworkin : –). This insight is similar to Nietzsche’s that even the most absolute critique of morality remains grounded in a will to truth, which is not the remainder of an ideal but is ‘this ideal itself in its strictest, most spiritual formulation, esoteric through and through, with all external additions abolished, and thus not so much its remnant as its kernel’ (Nietzsche : ). However, while Nietzsche sees this as reason to doubt the practice of truth itself, Dworkin interprets this as a call to reaffirm truth’s unity. In his view, even the most profound relativism retains a standpoint from which the impossibility of judgment can be articulated. Thus, the arguments of positivists, deconstructionists, and all those in between suffer from the same basic flaw: they rely on an external form of skepticism that looks beyond itself for justification, seeking an Archimedean point from which one may judge  C H A R L E S OL N E Y Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core morality from outside morality (Dworkin : ). But since such a point cannot exist, any justification must come from within. Therefore, Dworkin argues, moral judgment must be regarded as a single, unified set of interpretive obligations. There are no objective, bare truthsin moraljustification; there are only reasons. If a claim is true, it is only because a reason makes it so. The resulting system of reasons is defined by interpretive consistency: moral claims are true when they fit together with other moral claims and false when they cannot be incorporated into the fabric of a moral universe. There is no standpoint from which to evaluate truth outside these moral claims. It is, as the saying goes, turtles all the way down. Moreover, since external resolution is impossible, ‘the argument ends when it meets itself, if it ever does’ (Dworkin : ). This does not, however, mean that truth is simply up for grabs. After all, ‘morality is in the eye of the beholder’ is a self-refuting claim, since it relies on a will to truth that exceeds the scope of its argument. Durable disagreement over the nature of morality is inevitable, but this does not disprove the unity of value; it merely reveals the need for further interpretive refinement (Dworkin : ). All claims are moral, but the only truthful moral claims are those that affirm the possibility of a shared interpretive obligation. If this is correct, then the essential moral object is not truth itself, but instead is a fidelity to the search for truth, and the unifying structure of moral reason is the principle of responsibility and mutual respect (Dworkin : ). II. The Role of History: Fidelity or Transcendence? Dworkin believes that the hedgehog’s approach, which treats law as merely ‘a branch, a subdivision, of political morality’ provides a unified picture of the world (Dworkin : ). The seed of this idea was present in his earlier formulation of law as integrity, but that seed could only reach its potential once detached from the confines in which it had been formulated. It is worth dwelling for a moment on precisely what is sacrificed in this move. Law as integrity was defined by the productive tension between two distinct interpretive responsibilities: ‘best light’ and ‘fit’. To interpret a law in the best light is to attach it to a larger process of moral judgment. By contrast, ‘fit’ means that judges are tasked with seeing a thing as the best version of that thing and not some other thing. This requirement of fit signifies that ‘the history or shape of a practice or object constrains the available interpretations’ (Dworkin : ). Here, it is worth noting that Dworkin approvingly cites Gadamer, ‘whose account of interpretation as recognizing, while struggling against, the constraints of history strikes the right note’ (Dworkin : ). The Progressive Case against Tradition In Justice for Hedgehogs, Dworkin splits apart the relationship of fit and best light. Now, the best version of law is simply the one that expresses its value in a unified fashion. The frame of reference is one’s own moral universe, which should include fidelity to the object of inquiry, but which always conceives of that fidelity as T H E D I F F E R E N D O F J U S T I C E  Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core conceptually contained within to the larger demand for unity. Accordingly, while a historical perspective will often be crucial to grasping the contours of moral truth, there is no obligation to honor such history beyond the value contained in the content of its moral claims. To do otherwise would trap the moral structure of reason within the amber of a particular historical tradition (Dworkin, : , , ). The danger here is particularly acute in the case of extreme evils located in a collective past. Why treat decisions such as Dred Scott or Korematsu with integrity? They are historical facts, but facts whose validity should be actively written out of existence (See Donato ; Fleming ). Indeed, for Drucilla Cornell and Nick Friedman (), Dworkin’s new approach is laudable precisely because he now treats history as merely one moral object among others. By rejecting ‘the precedence of the past over both the present and the future’ he returns judgment to its proper location: a progressive present tense (Cornell and Friedman : ). Habermas () clarifies the significance of this move, arguing that the inherent imbalances within history necessarily structure interpretation. As such, hermeneutics is subject ‘to the repressivity of forces which deform the intersubjectivity of agreement as such and which systematically distort everyday communication. It is for this reason that every consensus, as the outcome of an understanding of meaning, is, in principle, suspect of having been enforced through pseudo-communication’ (Habermas : ). Hermeneutic engagement requires good faith from all parties, but history can never play such a role. Its deformities, therefore, will be incorporated into the present without challenge, thus ‘nullifying or rendering absurd our emancipatory aspirations’ (How : ). In this way, the unbridgeable prejudices of the past are built into the hermeneutic relationship by the simple act of taking them as legitimate. According to the progressive argument, Dworkin was correct to dispense with his Gadamerian inclinations. The hermeneutic perspective is a useful model for approaching interpretive engagement, but fidelity to the text is a means for pursuing truth, not an independent value. By the same light, tradition is valuable only insofar as a unified conception of value gives us good reason to regard it as such. Past wrongs are not to be respected simply because they are part of a continuing order, but instead should be excised to help sustain a genuinely unified moral order. The ideal act of interpretation draws the external object out of its original time and place to make it present. It expresses the ever-evolving truth of an omnipresent now, in which the past is never truly past but instead is renewed by the constant obligation of justification. Gadamer and Dworkin’s Lost Horizons To Dworkin, this move away from Gadamerian hermeneutics is necessary. It is worth considering, however, whether the opposite move might have been superior. After all, Gadamer would likely argue that Dworkin’s recuperative attitude toward truth is the real problem. The unity of value implies that every dissonance may ultimately be expressed through incorporation; the appearance of the gap disappears in the expression of underlying truth. But what if the presence of difference is the very condition of thought?  C H A R L E S OL N E Y Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core For Gadamer, understanding is not something possessed by subjective agents but instead is implicit in the structure of conversation itself (Gadamer : ). Truth, to the extent that it is possible, is constituted by the space between a subject and a text; it is not something discovered or articulated by the subject. In this process, the enduring friction generated by the discontinuity between worlds is the necessary precondition for understanding. The Enlightenment has taught us to treat prejudice as an unadulterated negative, as the bane of objectivity and the prioritization of self-interest over justice. But this is itself a (specifically modern) prejudice: paradoxically, a prejudice against prejudice (Gadamer : ). The flaw of this approach is its desire to generate knowledge, as opposed to understanding—and thereby to achieve control rather than engagement (Gadamer : xxxii). Knowledge takes place within the boundaries of a horizon; it depends on the preformed network of concepts and effective history. The place of a subject in a particular moment provides her with a broad but finite horizon of potential understanding. Understanding, by contrast, shifts horizons. By engaging with a perspective outside of an effective history, one’s own perspective must also shift. Understanding only emerges when horizons overlap, provoke conflict, fuse. It requires openness as well as tension. Thus, what Dworkin diagnoses as holes in a unified order—the unfilled spaces between reasons and their justification, between subject and object, between past and present—Gadamer treats as necessary. A world without gaps would need no bridges and thus would produce no understanding (Gadamer : xxviii). Indeed, understanding is nothing but the temporary bridges built across these gaps. Rather than seeking to fill these holes, we should regard the lingering dislocation they produce as essential to meaning-making. By this argument, we might characterize Justice for Hedgehogs as terminally misguided. Faced with the inherent doubt that comes from fusing horizons—its imperfection and incompleteness—Dworkin shies away. He perceives this insecurity as dangerous, and therefore seeks to quash it under the weight of moral unity. But this task is ultimately fruitless. He will inevitably reach, as Wittgenstein might say, a bedrock where his spade is turned and whatever justification may be supplied beyond this point is simply ‘a kind of ornamental coping that supports nothing’ (Wittgenstein : §). And there, faced with the seeming nihilism at the heart of interpretation, he ‘would rather will nothingness than not will’ (Nietzsche : ). From the hermeneutical perspective, then, Dworkin’s choice to double down on the principle of unity is a colonizing act, an attempt to compel coherence and meaning. This effort can only produce a false form of closure, in which the interpreter claims to discover truth that she herself has in fact created. In the name of truth, the hedgehog eliminates the possibility of understanding. III. Interpretation as Redemption: The Formal Unity of Interpretive Approaches The debate described in the previous section—progressive unity versus hermeneutic disjuncture—is organized primarily around a presumed break between Dworkin’s T H E D I F F E R E N D O F J U S T I C E  Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core old and new approaches. Where he once aligned with the Gadamerian model of effective history and thereby sided (at least partially) with the foxes, he has now chosen the logic of the hedgehog. Framed in this way, the key question raised by Justice for Hedgehogs is simply whether this choice is justified. Was Dworkin right to reduce the force of history, to side with the progressive model of free-floating reason? However, the caesura between these perspectives is smaller than it seems. While different in some respects, these approaches might best be understood as a parallax effect: the result of looking at the same phenomenon of judgment from different vantage points. Ultimately, each of these interpretive approaches is founded on a redemptive narrative, which treats the persistent fact of difference as an opportunity for the recuperation of order. The meaning of this process may be characterized in an almost limitless variety of ways—with fidelity to an interpretive past or to a timeless morality being merely a small subset of the possibilities. But in any case, the one thing justice cannot mean is the straightforward admission of unjustifiable violence at the heart of political unity. Such violence is the theological remainder, the necessary byproduct of endless and irresolvable debates over interpretation (Schmitt ). We are asked to justify, but all justification occurs only against the background of debts that may never be repaid, owed to those whose very existence was nullified to establish the specific, material present within which such debates take place. The full ramifications of this effect are explored below in section IV. First, however, the convergence of these seemingly distinct approaches must be mapped. The Redemptive Core of Law as Integrity To define the structure of this redemptive impulse, it is helpful to start with Dworkin, and the supposed shift from law as integrity to the unity of value. What we find is far more similarity than difference in these approaches. Indeed, every significant element of the argument from Justice for Hedgehogs is prefigured in the earlier work. For the early Dworkin, the commitment to the past as a distinct obligation is real, but is nevertheless framed as a mechanism for stabilizing the present coherence of moral reason (Hutchinson ). Judgment means regarding the mistakes of the past as negated principles. We honor the story of the law through its progressive reconstitution: binding together past and present by conceiving of mistakes as amenable to rectification through the law—rather than through revolution. This teleology of progress provides a mechanism for affirming the principles of a moral order against its historical failures (Meister : –). The contiguous principles that unify a constitutional history come to life precisely through their progressive incorporation into the present. Understood this way, the obligation of fit was never a genuine commitment to the externality of history, but rather was an internal obligation of reason. Its emphasis on unity always required incorporation of the past into the present; the river could only flow in one direction. The priority of moral coherence is absolute, while the obligation to an imagined past endlessly recedes.  C H A R L E S OL N E Y Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core Therefore, Justice for Hedgehogs merely states clearly what was already implicit: both integrity and the unity of value stem from the impulse to read the positive values of a moral order against its failures, to redeem the system by situating its core principles against those past injustices. Doing so honors the continuity of community while redeeming what we now take to have been erroneous (See Balkin ). To speak of justice, in either case, is to affirm a basic shared human dignity, which shows that no one is irredeemable. Dworkin’s interpretive method was never in need of rescue from a conservative reliance on tradition over present judgment; rather, it needed a philosophical justification for why the present is permitted to colonize its subject. Justice for Hedgehogs provides that justification, by treating it not as colonization but instead as redemption. The Redemptive Core of Gadamer’s Hermeneutics What then of Gadamer? Does he not provide an alternative approach, one untainted by such universalizing structures? If law as integrity is a failed hermeneutics, one implicitly guided by the hedgehog’s impulse, why paint Gadamer with the same brush? After all, his approach is built around active resistance to the incorporative techniques of enlightenment thought, which collapse the incommensurable gap between past and present into a unifying logic of reason (Gadamer: –). However, as Jacques Derrida argues, the very attempt to theorize this gap itself imposes a form of unity. Even as Gadamer attempts to evade the logic of rationality, his interpretive procedures necessarily reimpose a will to meaning. This is because ‘we can pronounce no single destructive proposition which has not already had to slip into the form, the logic, and the implicit postulations of precisely what it seeks to contest’ (Derrida : –). The very act of interpretation involves the generation of order. In particular Derrida focuses on the concept of ‘good will’, which, for Gadamer, is the necessary condition for successful interpretation. It does not insist on the construction of a single truth but rather seeks the understanding that is possible among truths. This permits consensus without agreement (Gadamer : ). This notion of good will, however, is ill-equipped for the hidden traps and closures that Derrida sees as intrinsic to communication. Even more, good will is infeasible in the context of an unreliable interlocutor. For good will to produce understanding, both the subject and object of interpretation must remain open to the other (Gadamer : ). But this cannot account for objects of inquiry that actively seek to block shared meaning. For example, this is a problem in psychoanalysis, where ‘the aim is to understand, not what the other wants to be understood, but exactly that which the patient wishes to conceal’ (Shapcott : ). Once again, the fact of historical wrongs clarifies this problem. When interpreting the law, one must constantly struggle with a legal history replete with grave exclusions. The Gadamerian interpreter, facing such a reality, is forced to search for a foothold of good faith—a way in which the exclusion may be understood without being affirmed. This is not likely to be framed as a project of ‘justice’, but T H E D I F F E R E N D O F J U S T I C E  Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core the resemblance is uncanny. Just as with Dworkin, the desire to understand the legal order implicitly contains an expression of faith in the potential good will of its structure. One must be willing to read its failures as horizons not yet fused or else abandon the prospect of interpretation as such. This faith, as with Dworkin, enacts a narrative of continuity. Moreover, the manner in which horizons may be fused depends on a hidden form of exclusion, stemming from the necessity for mutuality. While engagement may shift horizons, it can only occur if both sides are willing to put themselves at risk. This means that the ‘hermeneutic experience extends as far as does reasonable beings’ openness to dialogue’ (Gadamer : , emphasis added). While he intends this to clarify the essentially limitless scope of dialogue, it is crucial to note how casually Gadamer slips into the language of reasonableness. Indeed, as framed here it is quite difficult to distinguish meaningfully his theoretical structure from that of Rawlsian political liberalism. Both require the posited framework of the reasonable—defined as the willingness to converse on terms that that arise out of but do not impose any particular effective history (See Rawls : –). Gadamer fills this concept of reasonableness with less content than Rawls, to be sure, but this does not alter the basic formal similarity. Therefore, Gadamer is no better equipped than the liberals to deal with the circularity of this concept. What distinguishes reasonable subjects (with whom understanding may be achieved) from enemies (who seek only destruction)? Only the judgment of reasonable subjects—who mark themselves as reasonable through their willingness to engage. The unreasonable other is thus conceptually essential —it clarifies the capacity for dialogue through its absence—but also necessarily excluded (See O’Neill , Schmitt ). The result is a form of stasis, in which such unreasonable outlaws linger in a sort of perpetual limbo and mark the undefined exteriority of hermeneutic engagement. In Derrida’s terms, this reveals that the supposed ‘continuity of rapport’ at work in hermeneutic understanding is in fact built upon ‘the interruption of rapport, a certain rapport of interruption’ (Derrida : ). Redemptive Unities: The Search for Truth Each of these interpretive models is struggling with the same problem: how to articulate a concept of fit that does not self-destruct under the weight of an interpretive unity. Because none can accomplish this goal, they default to redemptive stories, whereby the remaining gap between what is best and what is understood may be justified. In one form or another, that gap is treated as an invitation to justification. In this respect, they all construct theodicies, interpretive models meant not just to explain the fact of evil but also to incorporate that evil into a broader narrative of the good. In a certain sense, therefore, Dworkin’s argument in Justice for Hedgehogs is correct. He quite brilliantly demonstrates that there is no ‘outside’ to value; it encompasses the entire universe. Further, this universality of value is intrinsic to every interpretive effort. However much an approach might pay fealty to the notion of openness, that commitment is founded on the imposition of order. The  C H A R L E S OL N E Y Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core hedgehog’s justice is therefore neither more progressive nor more universal than any other approach: it merely expresses those features with greater clarity. However, this is a hollow victory. Dworkin has revealed a universal structure, but in the process has lost hold of its meaning. As I explain in the next section, the redemptive impulse may inflect all moral claims, but in doing so it merely clarifies the impossible task of expunging the ghosts that haunt our political universe. IV. The Differend of Justice: Violence beyond Redemption Dworkin convincingly argues for an infinite system of value—an unbounded universe of moral claims. However, this infinity remains sharply constrained. Within it, one may travel endlessly, but the journey only leads in a circle back to the same location. It is therefore a secular infinity, one without beginning or end, an eternal present. The different techniques of interpretation (law as integrity, the unity of value, Gadamerian hermeneutics, utilitarianism, positivism, the original position, etc.) each generates its own flavor of infinity, but all of these approaches share the same underlying problem, a variation of Russell’s paradox: they seek to create a set of all things but cannot account for the system of thought necessary to generate such a set in the first place (Barrow : –, –). In the case of the law, this obscures the lingering necessity of legal decision—something that can be justified by, but never incorporated into, the unity of value. This section seeks to clarify the extent of this limit. It does so by applying Lyotard’s concept of the differend to the practice of moral reason. To explain: the differend is a lingering injury that falls outside the accepted terms of the language game in which it is manufactured. It cannot be addressed on the terms of a shared interpretive structure because it represents pain beyond articulation. It is like an untranslatable word, whose meaning is altered when expressed in a different language. To the extent that it can be filtered into a new language it loses an element of its own identity; it becomes a new, slightly different concept. For example, any attempt to litigate the Holocaust founders on the incapacity for legal concepts to capture the world-destroying nature of that act. To litigate the crime washes away its unique texture and renders it banal (Lyotard : –). The well-meaning attempt to express fidelity to victims falters in the face of the ineffable reality of the act. In making this argument, Lyotard treads on familiar ground. Like Dworkin and Gadamer, he also emphasizes the endlessly recursive process of understanding, the impossibility of stepping outside interpretation. For him this is expressed: ‘To doubt that one phrases is still to phrase’ (Lyotard : xi). Just as an argument against moral obligation is still a moral argument, to reject the representational capacity of language is still to make a representational claim. Any attempt to limit the scope of interpretation, therefore, is self-contradictory. The ‘last phrase’ ceases to be final as soon as it is named as such (Lyotard : ). As such, Lyotard shares the perception that judgment is limited to endless recirculation with no objective resolution. The key difference is his attitude toward this limitation of reason. For Dworkin, the lack of external certainty proves the unity of value; if there can be no permanent T H E D I F F E R E N D O F J U S T I C E  Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core foundations, all that is left is a secular world of linked justifications, a closed universe. But what if the question of externality is divorced from the question of foundations? Self-justifying grounding may be impossible, but this does not foreclose the possibility of a second type of external object: remainders. While foundations are positive externals—they provide the secure basis from which a moral claim may be advanced—remainders are negative exclusions. They exist in a space beyond reason and evade explanation or even comprehension (Badiou : ). The defining feature of every concept of justice in our secular age is its attitude toward such remainders. In every case an attempt is made to formalize them, to comprehend them, to make them explicable. They cannot be erased in a material sense—violence and exclusion are indelible features of a world without God—but they can be neutralized. This entails fitting them into a conceptual scheme, sorting them, explicating them. As soon as one is capable of correctly formulating the act of violence, it ceases to be arbitrary; it is given meaning through its articulation. Justice is therefore the practice by which distinctions are drawn between forms of exclusion. In the first case are those who suffer for no cause (victims). In the second case are those who inflict suffering without justification (perpetrators). The line is drawn in this fashion in order to generate legitimacy for a certain kind of violence: the punishment meted out by a collective will. The collectivization of judgments on violence is necessary to restrain victims from lashing out and thus becoming perpetrators of violence themselves (Meister : ; see also Locke : – , ). In a very real sense, justice is nothing else but the performance of this distinction. It comes into being through the administration and organization of violence—the construction of formal mechanisms through which the disjuncture of injustice is redeemed, and thereby reincorporated into the legal order (Benjamin ). Formative Violence Material violence, then, generates the tension through which justice may come into being. Law’s core function is to concretize this distinction, to divide the world between legitimate and illegitimate violence. This task, however, utterly founders when it encounters violence that is neither (Derrida ). This is a formative violence, which exceeds the politics of gain and loss. It cannot be expressed in terms of justice, but is a revolutionary and creative violence—the clearing away of space so that normative order may be written. The violence of this enclosure is never merely conceptual but instead depends on the active destruction of those who threaten to disrupt it (Schmitt : –). The American case offers a particularly stark picture: the continent-wide project of Indian extermination that was necessary for the formation of a new United States (Meister : ; Gerstle : –; Saxton : ). However, the problem is not uniquely American. Every legal order is built on the ashes of that which came before. We are all ‘taking the place (or living on the ruins) of a vanished civilization’ (Meister : ). If it is turtles all the way down, then each turtle is birthed out of the ashes of those that came before.  C H A R L E S OL N E Y Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core Such violence—the initial expression of law’s aporia—is permanently locked into the past. It therefore exceeds any potential for remedy. It is the lingering silence of those who have been cast aside by history: the differend of justice. The victims of this exclusion cannot be cast within the frame of ‘victim’ and ‘perpetrator’ because they no longer exist. There are no victims left, and the ruins of preexisting civilizations cannot ask for justice. At the same time, no one can be marked as perpetrator when all that remain are equally the beneficiaries of the absence in which their order has been formed. The community of justice, by the very logic of interpretive unity that binds them to the concept, cannot accept the thought of unredeemable collective communal guilt for a mass injustice. Instead, they must treat justice as the obligation to ‘deplore what happened to prior inhabitants without wishing that it hadn’t’ (Meister : ). Certainly, this is the story told by secular modernity: right and wrong may be judged only through the lens of finitude. However, Dworkin’s brilliant unification of all interpretive models under the framework of justice clarifies that formative violence must inevitably seep back into the practices of everyday justice. Because every judgment is linked together, no judgment is free of its origin. The battle must constantly be refought. Every ‘interruption’, to borrow Derrida’s phrase, must be brought into the fold, through violence if necessary. Such violence is justified because the alternative would be to acknowledge the existence of exclusion beyond the reach of justice. Further, this process can never be ended. In drawing the distinction between victim and perpetrator, the judge must always generate a third perspective capable of evaluation. This third standpoint necessarily lies outside the supposedly universal logic of justice. And any effort to incorporate that third will only generate a new position of judgment, against which the original concept may then be judged. This recursive impossibility for incorporation constitutes a ‘meta-differend’ intrinsic to the idea of discussion (Lyotard : ). Each individual case of injustice thus appears available for incorporation, but the position of judgment itself always lingers as a remainder. The goal of law, therefore, is always both an attempt to remedy injustice by incorporating it into the moral order and an effort to exterminate the lingering violence that defies incorporation. As such, even the fusing of horizons can never be truly open; it always includes an element of colonization: even if only in the characterization of that which refuses understanding to be ‘unreasonable’. The cover of legitimacy thus eradicates the particularity of the victim’s suffering. By fitting it into a scheme of ultimate redemption, it ‘ultimately preordains the irreducible experience of suffering to a foretold redemption, meaning that [it] doesn’t really allow suffering to be in its otherness but has already reduced it to sameness beforehand’ (Badiou : ). These logics of redemption serve a very specific purpose. They are not merely free-floating theories but instead are necessary and inevitable results of a system of law founded on the depoliticization of radical violence. The redemptive narrative isolates the fact of violence, modulates it, legalizes it. It treats the fact of violence as an inspiration to justification, to a logic of persuasion, whose goal is not to justify the coercive act to those upon whom it is exercised but instead is to justify T H E D I F F E R E N D O F J U S T I C E  Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core it to those who must enact it. To organize the concept of law around this goal entails drawing together a community who may then punish those who remain exterior. The force of law is justified entirely by the fact that such outlaws could have been persuaded but chose not to be. Law’s Violence: Pain and Legal Interpretation This problem is expressed well by Robert Cover (), in his excellent critique of Law’s Empire. For Cover, Dworkin’s approach is dangerous because it focuses on the procedure of justification and writes out the existence of the subject upon whom this law is written. The outlaw who suffers the decision is reduced to being nothing but the receptacle of legal violence. For such a person the law produces no redemption but only the bare fact of pain (Cover : ). Such pain, by its nature, can never be fit into the realm of justification; indeed, pain ‘destroys language itself’ (Cover : ). For example, in the case of torture, even a full confession cannot confirm the legitimacy of the process. The concern here is not that torture violates a moral principle (as Dworkin might argue) and is therefore unjustifiable. Such reasoning operates within the flux of moral persuasion, and is therefore susceptible to rewriting—with both substantive arguments (exceptional need) and/or procedural ones (appropriate restraint/due process) available to offer legitimation for the act. Dworkin would likely reject such justifications as incorrect assessments of moral obligation, but this is precisely the problem. Torture cannot be folded into a rational judgment about value because the entire purpose of torture is to break the rational world apart (Cover : ). Between the wielder and object of pain, no shared community is possible and ‘any commonality of interpretation that may or may not be achieved is one that has its common meaning destroyed by the divergent experiences that constitute it’ (Cover : ). Consider the scenes at the end of , in which O’Brien tortures Winston Smith with the goal of completely realigning Smith’s subjectivity. The experience of pain destroys resistance not by overwhelming the desire for freedom but rather by breaking the capacity to understand freedom as anything other than slavery (Orwell, , –). It may seem overly dramatic to analogize torture and the abstract workings of a legal system, but at root they employ the same logic. The law is not simply an abstract phenomenon; it ‘is built only to the extent that there are commitments that place bodies on the line’ (Cover : ). And the important binding feature of law is not the people’s willingness to affirm its principles but rather is their commitment to make themselves martyrs to its purpose, that is: to commit violence in its name. That such martyrdom has become highly formalized and abstract in the modern world does not change the underlying fact. Judicial decisions that purport to honor the hermeneutic process necessarily overlook the institutional structure of those judgments; they miss the ‘pre-legal’ feature of legal interpretation (Goorden ). The law is a political object, one held together by the collective administration of violence in the name of (a particular concept of)  C H A R L E S OL N E Y Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core justice (Dallmayr : –). And the interpretive community of law is always a finite body built against its excluded remainders. In this way, the formative violence of law is manifested in every decision. Law’s structural exclusion is not simply the abstract loss of faded civilizations; it is instead carried forward through the act of interpretation and made present in every new decision. As a permanent disjuncture in the concept of justice, formative violence ensures the continual reenactment of daily exclusion. The judgment is made to distribute pain, but that pain cannot be conceptually fit into the normative order of justice. It is neither just nor unjust. It simply is. And behind the veil of interpretation lie only material bodies that suffer, bereft of law’s redemption. Cover’s analysis of the world-destroying fact of pain demonstrates the very real consequences. A brick wall of implicit violence blocks the persuasive appeal of law from obtaining universality. In the body of the accused criminal, its terminal breakdown is made clear. Recall Dworkin’s argument that moral reason is founded on the doctrine of responsibility: that one must treat others as objectively important in order to make any moral claim. The dark underside of this premise is made clear in an innocent-seeming passage about mutual recognition. Because respect is mutual, he argues, moral agents must respect others ‘only so far as they accept the burden of responsibility . . . because only then do they really accept that equal importance’ (Dworkin : ). The criminal facing the violence of incarceration, or the exterminated ghosts of the past, will find little comfort in this sense of mutual respect. V. Justice and the Limits of Reason The desperate need of every political philosophy is to translate unlimited (and thus incomprehensible) violence into ‘injustice’. Once so rendered, such exclusion can be redeemed by isolating its pain as past and drawing its injunction for reparation into the present. However, such redemption is always incomplete, founded as it is on the erasure of that violence which cannot be transmuted in this way. To illustrate this process, I have explored three seemingly distinct interpretive modes. Using the framework set up in Justice for Hedgehogs, the apparent differences collapsed into a larger unity: the goal of redemption. Each one, in a distinct way, reflects the underlying logic of life in an inter-messianic, secular age. They arise from the need to cope with irresolvable doubt. That coping takes the form of second chances. Hope is never extinguished but instead comes to life through the continual process of redeeming evil. What has become clear is that this approach founders on its conceptual limits. The interpreting subject lives within a moral universe but cannot grasp the formative violence that is enacted by a moral universe (its differend). And this interpretive gap is occluded by the concept of justice. Dworkin attempts to resolve the tempestuous battle that has defined modern politics—legality versus legitimacy, morality versus politics. He observes a perpetual indeterminacy and refuses to collapse the contradiction by choosing a side. Armed with a deep faith that goodness may be found within the scope of T H E D I F F E R E N D O F J U S T I C E  Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core human reason, he reaches into Schrödinger’s box and draws out a hedgehog. However, this very faith is itself the perfect realization of reason’s limit. By sanding away all the rough edges from the normative case for justice and expressing it in all-encompassing terms, Dworkin takes us onto ‘slippery ice where there is no friction and so in a certain sense the conditions are ideal, but also, just because of that, we are unable to walk. We want to walk: so we need friction. Back to the rough ground!’ (Wittgenstein : §). That is: by treating justice as a subject of reason, he removes it as far as possible from the active practice of law. If justice is simply a matter of persuasion, then the enactment of its precepts becomes relegated to mere enforcement. What is lost here is the way in which such enforcement, the delineation of a line between us and them, is the essence of judgment itself. In this, law’s violence is fully externalized; it becomes the differend of law. Justice for Hedgehogs, by seeking completely to eliminate the exclusions of politics that stem from a relativistic worldview, circles entirely around to meet itself on the other side. Its terminal point of enclosure is found by reversing its most basic maxim. If relativism is always a moral concept, then so is the opposite true: every moral concept is ultimately a form of relativism. And the more that justice is differentiated from the world-breaking fact of violence, the closer it comes to enacting precisely the violence it seeks to end. CHARLES OLNEY UNIVERSITY OF TEXAS AT RIO GRANDE VALLEY charles.olney@utrgv.edu References Badiou, Alain. () Five Lessons on Wagner. Translated by Susan Spitzer. London: Verso. Badiou, Alain. () Wittgenstein’s Antiphilosophy. Translated by Bruno Bosteels. New York: Verso. Balkin, Jack. () Constitutional Redemption: Political Faith in in an Unjust World. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Barrow, John. () The Infinite Book: A Short Guide to the Boundless, Timeless and Endless. New York: Pantheon Books. Benjamin, Walter. () ‘Critique of Violence’. In Marcus Bullock and Michael Jennings (eds.), Selected Writings, Vol. , – (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), –. Berlin, Isaiah. () The Hedgehog and the Fox: An Essay on Tolstoy’s View of History. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson. Cornell, Drucilla, and Nick Friedman. () ‘The Significance of Dworkin’s Non-Positivist Jurisprudence for Law in the Post-Colony’. Malawi Law Journal, , –. Cover, Robert () ‘Violence and the Word’. Yale Law Journal, , –. Dallmayr, Fred. () ‘Hermeneutics and the Rule of Law’. In Gregory Leyh (ed.), Legal Hermeneutics: History, Theory, and Practice (Berkeley: University of California Press), –. Derrida, Jacques. () Writing and Difference. Translated by Alan Bass. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Derrida, Jacques. () ‘Three Questions to Hans-Georg Gadamer’. In Diane Michelfelder and Richard Palmer (eds.), Dialogue and Deconstruction: The Gadamer-Derrida Encounter (Albany: State University of New York Press), –.  C H A R L E S OL N E Y Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. http://orcid.org/0000-0002-8512-5181 mailto:charles.olney@utrgv.edu https://www.cambridge.org/core Derrida, Jacques. () ‘Force of Law: The Mystical “Foundation of Authority”’. In Drucilla Cornell, Michael Rosenfeld, and David Carlson (eds.), Deconstruction and the Possibility of Justice (New York: Routledge), –. Donato, James. () ‘Dworkin and Subjectivity in Legal Interpretation’. Stanford Law Review, , –. Dworkin, Ronald. () Law’s Empire. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Dworkin, Ronald. () Justice for Hedgehogs. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Fleming, James. () ‘Fidelity to Our Imperfect Constitution’. Fordham Law Review, , – . Gadamer, Hans Georg. () ‘Reply to Jacques Derrida’. In Diane Michelfelder and Richard Palmer (eds.), Dialogue and Deconstruction: The Gadamer-Derrida Encounter (Albany: State University of New York Press), –. Gadamer, Hans-Georg. () Truth and Method. New York: Continuum. Gerstle, Gary. () American Crucible: Race and Nation in the th Century. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Goorden, Dean. () ‘Dworkin and the Phenomenology of the “Pre-Legal”?’. Ratio Juris, , –. Habermas, Jürgen. () ‘The Hermeneutic Claim to Universality’. In Gayle Ormiston and Alan Schrift (eds.), The Hermeneutic Tradition: From Ast to Ricouer (Albany: State University of New York Press), –. Hart, H. L. A. () The Concept of Law. Oxford: Clarendon Press. How, Alan. () The Habermas-Gadamer Debate and the Nature of the Social: Back to Bedrock. Brookfield: Avebury. Hutchinson, Allan. () ‘Indiana Dworkin and Law’s Empire’. Yale Law Journal, , –. Locke, John. () Second Treatise of Government. In Peter Laslett (ed.), Two Treatises of Government (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), –. Lyotard, Jean-François. () The Differend: Phrases in Dispute. Translated by Georges Van Den Abbeele. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Meister, Robert. () After Evil. New York: Columbia University Press. Nietzsche, Friedrich. () On the Genealogy of Morals. Translated by Walter Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale. New York: Random House. O’Neill, Onora. () ‘Political Liberalism and Public Reason: A Critical Notice of John Rawls, Political Liberalism’. Philosophical Review, , –. Orwell, George. () . New York: Signet Classic. Prǐbáň, Jirí̌. () ‘The Time of Constitution-Making: On the Differentiation of the Legal, Political and Moral Systems and Temporality of Constitutional Symbolism’. Ratio Juris, , –. Rawls, John. () Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press. Saxton, Alexander. () The Rise and Fall of the White Republic: Class Politics and Mass Culture in Nineteenth Century America. London: Verso. Schmitt, Carl. () Political Theology: Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty. Translated by George Schwab. Cambridge, MA: Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press. Schmitt, Carl. () The Nomos of the Earth in the International Law of the Jus Publicum Europaeum. Translated by G. L. Ulmen. New York: Telos Press. Shapcott, Richard. () Justice, Community and Dialogue in International Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Wittgenstein, Ludwig. () Philosophical Investigations. Translated by G. E. M. Anscombe. New York: MacMillan. T H E D I F F E R E N D O F J U S T I C E  Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use. https://www.cambridge.org/core The Differend of Justice: Violence and Redemption in Dworkin's Justice for Hedgehogs Abstract The Unity of Value: Interpretation for Hedgehogs The Role of History: Fidelity or Transcendence? The Progressive Case against Tradition Gadamer and Dworkin's Lost Horizons Interpretation as Redemption: The Formal Unity of Interpretive Approaches The Redemptive Core of Law as Integrity The Redemptive Core of Gadamer's Hermeneutics Redemptive Unities: The Search for Truth The Differend of Justice: Violence beyond Redemption Formative Violence Law's Violence: Pain and Legal Interpretation Justice and the Limits of Reason References work_fseoxlznezadzabz7yazkz6xg4 ---- GENDERED VIOLENCE AND RESTORATIVE JUSTICE: THE VIEWS OF VICTIM ADVOCATES SARAH CURTIS-FAWLEY 32 CUMBERLAND AVE CUMBERLAND PARK, SA, 5041, AUSTRALIA 8-8357-0205 (HOME) 413-592-323 (MOBILE) SCURTISFAWLEY@YAHOO.COM KATHLEEN DALY SCHOOL OF CRIMINOLOGY AND CRIMINAL JUSTICE GRIFFITH UNIVERSITY, MT GRAVATT CAMPUS BRISBANE, QUEENSLAND 4111, AUSTRALIA 7-3875-5608 (FAX) 7-3875-5625 (OFFICE) K.DALY@MAILBOX.GU.EDU.AU We would like to thank the advocates who participated in this study for their enthusiasm and honesty, the Australian-American Fulbright Commission for supporting Sarah Curtis-Fawley to travel to Australia to undertake this research, and the Australian Research Council for supporting Kathleen Daly?s program of research on the race and gender politics of new justice practices. We would also like to extend special thanks to research assistant Brigitte Bouhours. Key Words: Restorative justice, gendered violence, victim advocates 1 ABSTRACT The use of restorative justice for gendered violence has been debated in the feminist literature for some time. Critics warn that it is inappropriate because the process and outcomes are not sufficiently formal or stringent, and victims may be re-victimized. Proponents assert that a restorative justice process may be better for victims than court because it holds offenders accountable and gives victims greater ?voice.? This paper presents what victim advocates in two Australian states think about using restorative justice for gendered violence. We find that while victim advocates have concerns and reservations about restorative justice, most saw positive elements. 2 INTRODUCTION Victims of gendered violence1 have been able and encouraged to seek justice in a limited number of ways, either through civil mechanisms such as restraining orders or through the criminal justice system (see e.g., Estrich, 1986; Mills, 1999). Although these routes of redress may not sufficiently protect individual women or decrease violence against women and children, criminal law reform has been the top priority of feminists for three decades, propelled by what Martin (1998, p. 168) deems an ?irresistible pressure?to make prosecutions easier and punishments more severe.? Feminist efforts to reform law and legal process have resulted in significant transformation at all levels of the justice system?s response to gendered violence, from police practice to the cross-examination of victim- witnesses (see e.g., Esteal, 1998). Still, the mood amongst feminists remains somber because the evidence suggests that from a victim?s perspective, little has changed (e.g., Hengehold, 2000; Presser & Gaarder, 2000; Spohn & Horney, 1992). As Heath and Naffine (1994, p. 32) observe, ?perhaps we had been lulled into believing that legislative reform meant progress.? Despite decades of legal reform, the vast majority of victims of sexual, domestic, and family violence still do not report offences to the police, and prosecution rates for gendered violence are still amongst the lowest for all offences (see e.g., Cook, David, & Grant, 2001; Douglas & Godden, 2002; Holder, 2001); victims have negative experiences in police interviews (Centre Against Sexual Assault, 1997); and when cases do go to trial, victims face long and distressing court processes (New South Wales Department for Women, 1996). Feminists are now ?questioning anew the ability of law by itself? to deliver justice to victims (Frohmann & Mertz, 1995, p. 829) and are looking outside the established criminal justice system for ways forward. 1 We use the term ?gendered violence? as an umbrella concept that captures Liz Kelly?s (1988) idea of a continuum of violence: child sexual abuse, incest, sexual assault, rape, domestic violence, and family violence. While acknowledging that gendered violence does occur in the context of same-sex relationships, and that women can victimize men, our focus is on male violence against adult women and male and female children. 3 In the past decade, restorative justice has been proposed as a promising means of responding to gendered violence (Braithwaite & Daly, 1994; Daly, 2002a; Hudson, 1998, 2002; Morris, 2002a; Morris & Gelsthorpe, 2000). Academic feminists have responded to these calls with skepticism, concern, and cautious interest, and a burgeoning critical literature has grown (see e.g., Strang & Braithwaite, 2002). Compared with the energetic debate occurring in academic circles, we know little about how victim advocates and service providers view the idea of restorative justice. Specifically, what do the people who work with victims every day think about the potential and perils of restorative justice? This article explores the views of Australian victim advocates on restorative justice. We find that in contrast to what many think ? that advocates are against alternatives to criminal justice ? advocates hold more pragmatic views on how to best deliver justice to victims. The advocates interviewed for this study were in fact more receptive to restorative justice than policy makers and academic commentators may think, and even we had initially imagined. Our article begins with a review of the literature on restorative justice and its potential applications for gendered violence. Next, we present the study context and methods. We then turn to these major themes arising from the interviews: advocates? recognition of the limits of the current justice system, yet a desire to rely upon it; their knowledge about and understandings of restorative justice; their perceptions of the benefits and pitfalls of restorative justice for gendered violence; and their views on optimal restorative justice practices for victims. Restorative justice triggers both hope and fear among victim advocates, and these different reactions can be traced, in part, to their varied experiences with and understandings of it. 4 RESTORATIVE JUSTICE AND GENDERED VIOLENCE A significant problem in researching and writing about restorative justice (RJ) is that people have disparate understandings and definitions of it (Crawford & Newburn, 2003, chaps 1 & 2; Daly, 2002b). Moreover, people get stuck in having a too literal interpretation of the words restorative or restoration. Although a major RJ proponent argues that ?restorative justice [is] about restoring victims, restoring offenders, and restoring communities? (Braithwaite, 1999, p. 1), we argue that RJ is better seen as a nominal concept that stands for a set of activities (see below), rather than as literally and narrowly being about ?restoring.? This conceptual shift is important in debating the appropriateness of RJ in gendered violence for as Coker (2002, p. 143) argues ?the concept of restoration suggests that a prior state existed in which [a domestic violence] victim experienced significant liberty and the offender was integrated into the community? when ?neither [may be] true.? Flying under the RJ banner are practices in juvenile justice, criminal justice, family welfare and child protection. They include diversion from the formal court process, actions taken in parallel with court decisions, meetings between offenders and victims at any stage of the criminal process (from arrest, pre-sentencing, and prison release), or meetings held for child protection cases. For criminal matters, in general, RJ typically contains these elements and set of activities: ? Offenders have admitted to the offence (or have chosen not to deny). ? Offenders and their supporters have a face-to-face meeting with a victim (or a victim representative) and a victim?s supporters, although having a face-to-face meeting is not essential. There may be other relevant people present, such as police officers or victim advocates. ? The process is informal, although the person organizing and running a meeting establishes the ground rules for participants (such as people must listen to each other and everyone has a chance to speak). 5 ? Discussion and decisions taken rely on the knowledge and decision-making capacities of lay actors rather than legal actors (although diversionary conferences generally have a police officer present). ? The aims are to reduce victim fear and anger toward the offender, for the victim to ?tell the story? of how the crime affected him or her, for the offender to acknowledge the harm and the negative consequences the crime caused a victim, for the offender to apologize, and for the offender to make up for what s/he did (?repair the harm?) by penalties agreed to. The major kinds of RJ practices include conferences, circles and sentencing circles, and a variety of victim-offender mediation processes (see Kurki, 2000). The history of RJ is contested. Some suggest that it was the ?dominant model of criminal justice throughout most of human history for all the world?s peoples? (Braithwaite, 1999, p. 2), a claim that is ?quickly refuted by any serious look at the literature of legal anthropology? (Bottoms, 2003, p. 88) (see further in Johnstone, 2002). What is not contested is the phenomenal growth and worldwide popularity of the idea in a short span of time. As discussed in Daly and Immarigeon (1998, pp. 23-29), three streams of activism and thought propelled the rise of informal justice in the 1970s and 80s, and RJ in the 1990s: major social movements of the 1960s (e.g., Civil Rights, Women?s Movement, Victim?s Movement, Prisoners? Rights), particular practices and programs (e.g., victim-offender mediation, conferencing, circles), and academic theories and research (e.g., informal justice, reintegrative shaming, feminist theories of justice). The term restorative justice came into widespread use in the mid-1990s, having been applied after the fact to existing programs or legislation. For example, when New Zealand passed its historic legislation in the late 1980s (Children, Young Persons and Their Families Act 1989), which created family group conferences for adolescent offenders, there was no reference to restorative justice in the legislation. Likewise, the first Australian state to legislate diversionary conferences for juvenile cases, South Australia, made no reference to restorative justice in the statute (Young Offenders Act 1993). Legislation establishing conferencing for juvenile offenders 6 has since been passed in all but one Australian jurisdiction (Daly & Hayes, 2001). One noteworthy feature is that with the exception of New Zealand and the Australian states of South Australia and Queensland, conferencing is prohibited in cases of sexual assault, and typically also for domestic or family violence. Conferencing is now being piloted or under consideration for adult offenders in parts of Australia and New Zealand, and here too we find that cases of domestic violence and sexual assault have been placed beyond the reach of conferencing. One reason that gendered violence is off the RJ agenda is that academic feminists and victim advocates have made compelling arguments against it. An early Australian document, which continues to exert significance, is a position paper by the National Committee on Violence Against Women (Astor, 1991; see also Astor, 1994). Astor argued against mediation in cases of domestic violence, and her concerns are enshrined today in the advocacy and academic literature. A critical focus by some feminists on RJ as just another type of mediation (which may mean mediating ?facts? between a victim and victimizer) as compared to what occurs in RJ conferences (where ?facts? are already admitted to by an offender and a larger group of people is present) has created much confusion in the debates on RJ and gendered violence. However, even with RJ conferencing in mind, feminists have raised many concerns (Busch, 2002; Coker, 2002; Goel, 2000; Hooper & Busch, 1996; Lewis et al., 2001; Stubbs, 1995, 2002), these being the most prominent: ? Informal processes risk re-victimizing victims (vis a vis power imbalances between victim and offender) or jeopardizing their safety. ? RJ will appear to be a ?soft option? or what Coker (1999, p. 85) terms ?cheap justice? to offenders and society. Serious offences like gendered violence ought to be treated seriously (that is, adjudicated in criminal court), not diverted from court to an alternative process. ? RJ may re-privatize gendered violence in ways that are harmful to women. 7 ? RJ has theoretical weaknesses, including its assumptions of a distant state and sufficient community opposition to domestic violence, and an under-theorization of the nature of domestic violence. RJ may also require additional state resources to adequately support both victim and offenders. Most of the critical feminist literature has focused on the problems of using RJ to respond to domestic violence. Of all crimes, domestic violence is unusual in that offences are not discrete events, but are typically characterized by an entrenched pattern that cycles from periods of calm to an escalation of violence to reconciliation (see e.g., Laing, 2002). While sexual assault can also occur in the context of domestic violence and as a pattern of abuse, many sexual assaults are discrete events. We consider both domestic violence and sexual assault, as well as other forms of violence such as child sexual abuse, in this article to examine RJ?s appropriateness for the range of cases falling under the umbrella of gendered violence, but it is important to recognize the distinctive problems each poses for victims in the legal process. The major hurdles for victims of sexual assault is the state?s ability to prove their case (see Frohmann [1998] on how prosecutors ?manage? adult sexual assault victims in cases with little evidence) and the impact of the trial process (see Eastwood [2003] on child sexual abuse victims), whereas the pressing concern for victims of domestic violence is to find methods of stopping the violence and securing a victim?s ongoing safety (Holder, 2001). While some victims of gendered violence wish to continue a relationship with an offender, others intend to sever it, and still others never had a relationship with the offender. These differing victim-offender relationships and victim needs must be considered in any legal response to gendered violence; as yet, this diversity of victim contexts and desires has posed major challenges to both feminist legal reformers and the established criminal justice system. Countering the critical literature, a growing number of academic feminists suggest that RJ practices may be more effective for diverse groups of victims compared to established criminal justice and formal legality (Blagg, 2002; Braithwaite & Daly, 1994; Daly, 2002a; Hudson, 1998, 2002, 2003; 8 Koss, 2000; Martin, 1998; Mills 2003; Morris, 2002a, 2002b; Morris & Gelsthorpe, 2000; Pennell & Burford, 2002; Presser & Gaarder, 2000; Snider, 1998). The major arguments for the merits of RJ are these: ? RJ offers a dialogic encounter between victims, offenders, and supporters. This increases the chances of condemning the violence in ways that are meaningful and consequential for offenders and victims, and it permits victims to tell their stories of the violence. ? RJ encourages admissions of offending, rather than denial (this is especially relevant in sexual assault cases where prosecution is especially difficult). ? The process and outcomes of RJ can validate victims? experience, provide assurances that they are not to blame for the violence, and give them greater priority in a legal process. ? RJ may offer more options to diverse groups of victims, some of whom do not want to formally prosecute the offender. ? RJ gives greater attention to lay, rather than legal views of crime, encouraging a more holistic understanding of the offence, rather than one confined to legal relevancies. A major irony in assessing the merits of RJ for gendered violence is a paucity of evidence to confirm or discount the critics? or proponents? claims. Feminists and victim advocacy groups have been successful in blocking the application of RJ for cases of gendered violence in most world jurisdictions. Therefore, there is a dearth of evidence on how RJ might work in practice rather than in theoretically best or worst case scenarios. Hudson (2002, p. 618) pointed to this problem when she wrote: Critics of the extension of restorative justice conferencing to offences such as domestic violence seldom address the question of whether there are standards and safeguards that could make it satisfactory for victims, whilst its proponents often fail to address questions of procedural safeguards or just outcomes for offenders. We agree with the critics that caution should be exercised, and that there is much we need to consider before RJ is introduced as one of several responses to gendered violence. At the same time, the 9 required learning cannot take place so long as principled positions are permitted to prevail in the absence of empirical evidence. Morris (2002b, p. 600) captures the qualities of infinite regress into speculation: There are occasions in this paper when I refer to a criticism which has been made without an empirical basis to support it but when, equally, I am not able to cite rebuttal evidence. All I can do then is to rebut speculation with speculation ? There is some evidence amidst the speculation. Critics of RJ cite studies of mediation of divorce cases, where couples have a history of violence, to show the effects of power imbalances (Astor, 1994; Cobb, 1997). They also cite an early study (Maxwell & Morris, 1993, p. 119), which showed that one-quarter of victims ?felt worse? after a conference, although Strang (2002) later observed that conference victims fared better than those whose cases went to court. From research on Canadian families, Pennell and Burford (2002, p. 108) believe that ?family group conferencing can stop family violence.? Coker (1999, p. 103) finds that Navajo peacemaking offers many benefits to battered women, but at the same time it can create ?real dangers for some women.? McGillivray and Comaskey?s (1999, p. 129) study of Canadian Indigenous women, who endured many years of partner violence, found that women wanted ?stiffer sentences and effective treatment programs.? They viewed ?community-based dispute resolution as partisan and subject to political manipulation? (pp. 143-4). These findings depart from Blagg?s (2002, p. 198) work with Australian Indigenous women, whose ?family violence paradigm? emphasizes interventions ?that stop abuse, cool out situations, open pathways to healing, with minimum intervention by the criminal justice system.?2 Our research on nearly 400 sexual offence youth justice cases that were finalized in court and by conference in South Australia (Daly, Curtis-Fawley, & Bouhours, 2003) finds that conferences outperform court in measures that matter to victims. Conference offenders admitted to their offending, whereas half the 2 Their differing conclusions arise, in part, from the study contexts. Blagg is analyzing family violence (partner violence, child abuse, and other kin violence) in remote Indigenous communities, and McGillivray and Comaskey have partner violence in mind. 10 court cases were dismissed; and for penalties, we find that conference offenders did more for victims (apology and acknowledgment), more for the community (through community service), and more for themselves (involvement in a therapeutic intervention) than offenders whose cases went to court. In reviewing the evidence on RJ and gendered violence, we would emphasize the varied phenomena being considered: is it partner violence by an adult male or a sexual assault by an adolescent male toward a sibling? Is it family violence in remote Indigenous communities or partner violence in urban areas? Is the RJ process specifically tailored to gendered violence, as in Pennell and Burford?s 2002 work, Intimate Abuse Circles (described in Mills 2003), and the program being undertaken by Hopkins, Koss, and Bachar (this volume), or not? These elements are crucial in understanding the nature and contexts of violence, and in making judgments on the appropriateness of an RJ process. We would also emphasise that RJ may warrant a justice response that is more vigorous than simply diversion from court (see Daly 2002), a point that Hudson (2002) has developed and elaborated upon. She argues that RJ ?could carry out the traditional function of criminal justice-- retribution, rehabilitation/reintegration, individual and public protection? (p. 626) in ways that current criminal justice practices have failed to do. THE STUDY: CONTEXT AND METHODS The study presented here is one component of a program of research on RJ and gendered violence, which has these sub-studies: (1) interviews with representatives of victim advocacy groups in South Australia and Queensland to elicit their views on RJ for cases of gendered violence (the study reported here); (2) interviews with Australian Indigenous and non-Indigenous women, working in policy and government in Queensland, to elicit their views on RJ for cases of gendered violence; (3) an archival analysis of nearly 400 sexual offence cases disposed of by court and conference over 6.5 years in South Australia (Daly, Curtis-Fawley, & Bouhours, 2003); and (4) an in-depth analysis of 15 conferences of sexual assault and domestic violence in South Australia, with a focus on what happened 11 at the conference and how victims were affected. The aim of these studies is to examine empirically and sympathetically the many claims and concerns that feminist scholars and victim advocates have lodged toward restorative justice. Unlike almost every other jurisdiction in the world, South Australia has been quietly pioneering the use of restorative justice, in the form of diversionary youth conferencing, for gendered violence (Daly, 2002a). Since the introduction of the Young Offenders Act 1993, over 150 sexual offence cases, with charges ranging from indecent exposure to rape, have been disposed of by family conference.3 In the latter part of 2001, we traveled to South Australia to undertake the first systematic empirical study of restorative justice and gendered violence. We were based in the Adelaide Youth Court for three months, gathering materials for the archival and in-depth analyses. This study reported here arose from Curtis-Fawley?s experience as an advocate in sexual assault and domestic violence service agencies in the United States. She wondered, what do victim advocates think of RJ as a response to gendered violence? With their significant experience, knowledge, and political influence, victim advocates have views that should be listened to and considered (see Strang, 2001 on the crime victim?s movement). At the same time, we recognize that advocates? claims about victims? needs may not be consistent with what crime victims say their needs and desires are (Fraser, 1989). The ?victim perspective? has been used (and, some would say, abused) to provide ammunition for the competing claims that victims want increased punitive sanctions (thus supporting more vigorous criminal law interventions), or that they ultimately want acknowledgement and apology rather than punishment (thereby providing support for alternatives such as RJ) (see Laster & Erez, 2000). While acknowledging that victims have wide ranging interests, experiences, and visions of justice, we believe 3 Conferencing began in South Australia in February 1994, and over time, the annual number of completed conferences for sexual offences has ranged from 12 to 25, with an average of 18 each year. It is difficult to estimate the number of domestic violence cases in the youth justice system because they are part of a larger category of common assault cases. From our in-depth analysis of ?domestic violence? cases (we put the term in quotes because the typical offence is a male or female adolescent assaulting his or her mother), we would estimate that 10 to 15 such cases are disposed each year by conference. Together, these two categories of offenses are a very small share (about 2%) of the annual number of cases disposed of by conference (ranges from 1600 to 1800 per year). 12 that victim advocates? years of experience in the field make them well positioned to speak authoritatively and reflectively about issues affecting victims, including alternative justice practices like RJ. During 2001-02, Curtis-Fawley conducted semi-structured interviews with representatives of 15 victim advocacy organizations in South Australia and Queensland (see Appendix 1). Victim advocacy was defined broadly to include organizations and government departments that advocate for or work on behalf of victims of gendered violence, at the level of policy or direct service. They included state- funded and non-government organizations, with a varied degree of feminist orientation. The organizations worked with or for victims of sexual assault, child sexual abuse, and domestic violence in a range of ways, including providing counseling, legal support, therapeutic interventions, policy work, lobbying, and community education. All but three study participants were female; nine were coordinators or directors of the organization, and the remainder were service providers. Most had considerable years of experience working in the field, on average ten years, although this ranged from one year to 26 years. The sample includes a wide range of organizations and perspectives, but because of its sample size, we cannot make strong generalizations from it. We see it as an exploratory study that can contribute to the literature and expand the range of viewpoints and voices on RJ and gendered violence. The interviews, which lasted, on average, 90 minutes, canvassed these areas: ? Advocates? views on the benefits and shortcomings of the criminal justice system?s handling of gendered violence. ? Advocates? understandings of what RJ is, and what they see as the benefits and concerns of using RJ for gendered violence. ? Advocates? views on the kinds of gendered violence that may be more or less appropriate for RJ or established criminal justice processes. 13 ? Advocates? views on optimal RJ practices, the risks of RJ for victims and offenders, and whether they would recommend that RJ be used for gendered violence. South Australia has been routinely using conferences in youth justice cases of gendered violence since the mid-1990s. By contrast, while Queensland has not proscribed gendered violence from conferencing, it has rarely been used in these cases. Until it was amended in 2003, Queensland?s juvenile justice legislation permitted victims the right to veto their case being referred to conference, which meant that police officers were wary of proposing a conference for serious offences.4 The consequence of these jurisdictional differences is that the South Australian advocates generally had more exposure to RJ than their Queensland counterparts, a difference that affected their views toward RJ. ?WE DON?T CALL IT A JUSTICE SYSTEM ANYMORE:? ADVOCATES? VIEWS ON CRIMINAL JUSTICE To understand the advocates? orientation towards restorative justice, the interview began with a set of questions about how the criminal justice system is and is not working for victims of gendered violence. All of the advocates had had some contact with the criminal justice system through their work, usually by providing information and support to victims. It was not surprising, then, that they spoke about the criminal justice system with a sense of urgency and frustration. The experience of one sexual assault and domestic violence advocate who has been working in the field for more than five years was typical: ?[the criminal justice system] is very tough on them, it is such a painful process. I 4 The Queensland Juvenile Justice Act 1992 was amended in 2002, and proclaimed in July 2003. Among other changes, the amendment abolished the right of victims to veto a referral to a community conference, although police must consider the harm suffered by the victim when deciding how to refer or dispose a case. In South Australia, police officers take the victim?s needs into account when making a decision to refer to court or conference, but victims do not have the right to over-ride the decision nor to direct how the case should be handled. Of course, if victims choose not to attend the conference, they can opt to send a representative or submit written or video statements. 14 have to say I only know of one woman who got a conviction? (QLD4).5 Advocates acknowledged that the standard practices in the criminal justice system put victims in the untenable position of risking further degradation and disappointment with very little chance of a ?successful? outcome, for example, a conviction. When the advocates were asked how the criminal justice system has been successful in responding to the needs of victims, they most commonly pointed to an increased awareness of gendered violence at all levels of the criminal justice system, including that of police and judicial officers. Legal reforms were also thought to make witnesses less vulnerable in the courtroom; for example, advocates mentioned the increased availability of closed circuit television and screens for young victims. Yet despite the successes and statutory changes brought about by feminist legal reform, the advocates recognized that there remained significant deficiencies in the justice system, one saying, for example: I think there is more awareness, but again I think it depends on what police station you call and who is on duty. It depends which magistrate you get. There?s a long way to go in terms of educating the police and the courts about the effects of violence. (SA4) All spontaneously made a negative comment about the justice system?s ability to effectively address gendered violence. These advocates? remarks are indicative: Victims see court as a kind of public humiliation ? there is a view that justice doesn?t happen, and very few cases are actually prosecuted. (SA7) Women are quite aware, usually, that the system will re-traumatize them, and they have to weigh that against whether they are going to go forward or not. (QLD5) When they actually get into the system, they feel that they are on trial ? It is a very embarrassing and humiliating process. I have never been so angry in all my life as watching a defense lawyer effectively attacking and undermining a [victim] on the stand. (QLD4) 5 The participants in this study were assured that their comments would be kept anonymous; therefore we do not identify the speaker of the quoted material. However, in order to show some of the differences between the organizational views in South Australia and Queensland, each quote will be followed by an identification code including the state (SA or QLD) and a random number for each organization. 15 The advocates spoke with exasperation on the shortcomings of the criminal justice system, noting that after decades of legal reform, much work remained to be done. Their concerns mirrored what socio-legal and feminist scholars have been saying for some time: ? victims are systematically re-victimized by their experiences with the system, from reporting the offence to the police through to their experiences in court as witnesses; ? sexual assault and domestic violence are under-reported and face many hurdles when prosecuted; ? if cases do proceed to court, the focus shifts to the victim?s credibility and behavior; ? because the system is adversarial, there is little scope for addressing violence between intimates or family members who wish to remain in a relationship, which is one reason that domestic violence victims may opt out of the system; and ? the system is incapable of dealing with child victims. These comments illustrate advocates? views on the inadequacies of the criminal justice system: I get called out and see these women who have been recently raped, and I think to myself, if I were in their position, knowing what I know, I wouldn't take it to court, I wouldn't pursue it. (SA3) The way the system is structured so women are not believed ? The onus is upon them to prove that an assault took place ? That's degrading and humiliating. So the act [of violence] is, and the court process further perpetuates that. (SA7) If a victim is three years old, she?s not going to be able to give evidence. She won?t be able to answer the questions, she won?t understand the concept of cross-examination, so it?s a useless exercise. People don?t understand that about half the children we see a year make quite clear allegations, but none of these cases make it to trial because it is a problem of evidence ? It puts incredible amounts of stress on the families, and creates a lot of problems for the child too. (SA2) The advocates? comments point to three major failures in the current criminal justice system. First, criminal proceedings rarely, if ever, validate a victim?s understanding of her experiences and rarely acknowledge that she is not to blame for the violence (Estrich, 1986). Second, the criminal court is unlikely to be an effective forum for addressing violence between intimates who will be in continuing relationships (Morris & Young, 2000). Finally, legal reform has thus far been unable to 16 create processes that are tailored to child victims? needs and capacities (Eastwood, 2003). As will be explored further in this paper, it is in precisely these areas that RJ has potential. The interviews bring to light a contradiction between continued efforts to reform the law and criminal justice system, and the recognition that such efforts will likely produce limited results. This contradiction reflects a paradox for feminist engagement with criminal law. Estrich (1986, pp. 1092- 93) put it well when she wrote, ?the law has reflected, legitimised, and enforced a view of sex and women which celebrates male aggressiveness,? and yet the over riding goal of many feminists is to ?write the perfect statute.? Despite the widespread view that the criminal justice system routinely harms victims in significant ways, most advocates in our study believed the justice system remained the best site for dealing with gendered violence. Typical of this position are the views of one advocate, who after describing the justice system as ?degrading and humiliating,? went on to say, ?we have not necessarily exhausted what is possible within the criminal justice system? (SA7). This persistent investment in legal reform puts advocates in the untenable position of continuing to defend and support a system they know fails most victims. ?IT?S ABOUT TRYING TO RESTORE SOME CONNECTION:? UNDERSTANDINGS OF RJ The lack of clarity about what does and does not constitute restorative justice has clouded the debate on its appropriateness for gendered violence. This confusion was evident in the interviews. Many victim advocates had difficulty answering the question, ?What does restorative justice mean to you?? Generally, advocates? descriptions of RJ focused on a victim-centered process that emphasizes healing over punishment. They also perceived RJ as an alternative to the current criminal justice system, which may allow for more flexible or creative outcomes. Statements from two advocates show how RJ is understood: 17 Because it is in its infancy, restorative justice is better understood as a challenge to the way we do things. In other words, it is another way of thinking about the administration of justice. (SA1) To me it means some kind of model that looks to put the victim back in the position that they were in before an offence was committed against them ?to give them an outcome that is more victim- driven, that the victim wants. (SA5) The advocates also focused on RJ?s potential to repair the relationship between the victim and the offender, which was perceived as a benefit by some, but also seen as major drawback by others, as exemplified by this advocate: Anything that gives the perpetrator access to a victim is doing the victim a disservice, is leaving her more vulnerable ? It is setting up the potential [for] reconciliation, and therefore more violence. (QLD6) Nine of the 15 advocates referred specifically to conferences as a form of restorative justice, and in fact, some believed it to be the only form. Many Queensland advocates linked RJ to a much- criticized state practice of mandatory referral to ?primary dispute resolution? (mediation) before the granting of Legal Aid, including cases that involve domestic violence. Of the 15 advocates, five believed that RJ is mediation dressed up in politically correct language. Some were concerned that governments? interest in RJ was driven by a need to reduce the costs of administering justice, not to provide better outcomes for crime victims. Several expressed positive understandings of RJ, but felt that its scope should be restricted to adolescent offending. One advocate warned that gendered violence was simply beyond RJ?s reach, saying, ?This isn?t about kids who shoplift? (SA7). Another advocate who was strongly opposed to RJ for gendered violence said: I guess I don?t have a problem with restorative justice itself. My real concern is that any chance that the system gets to water down crimes against women and children, they?ll take it, and restorative justice would be a prime example of that. (QLD5) Those expressing the greatest opposition to RJ throughout the interview were also those who were the most unsure of what it is. One said, for example, ?I am not sure I like it. I am not sure what it means? (QLD5). Very few said they had read the research literature on RJ; rather, they received information about it from television or radio reports, or through email networks. Several made statements like ?I don?t think my thinking [on RJ] is particularly sophisticated or advanced? (SA5), or 18 ?it?s a bit hazy to me really? (QLD7). These comments suggest the need for greater public education about RJ, drawing on both the theoretical and empirical literatures. ?RESTORATIVE JUSTICE CREATES OPPORTUNITIES:? PERCEIVED BENEFITS OF RJ The critical literature warns of the many ways that victims may be hurt by RJ. For example, existing power imbalances may be exacerbated, victim-offender meetings could lead to re- victimization, and RJ processes may be too informal and outcomes too lenient for the serious offending that constitutes gendered violence (Busch, 2002; Stubbs, 2002). In light of these concerns, an important and somewhat surprising finding from our study is that most advocates believed that RJ has something positive to offer victims of gendered violence, especially when compared with established criminal justice processes and outcomes. Of the 15 advocates, five were generally positive toward RJ; seven were cautiously positive, having many reservations, but also seeing potential benefits; and three were generally negative toward RJ, seeing the negative consequences to outweigh any benefits. All but two felt that RJ had something positive to offer victims of gendered violence. Those who had worked in the field the longest were more likely to hold positive views of RJ: they appeared more disillusioned with the established system, less optimistic that it could be sufficiently reformed, and were more receptive to expanding the range of options for victims. The advocates? orientations toward RJ were affected by their exposure to RJ practices. Most of the South Australian participants (five of eight) had had first-hand exposure to RJ, typically as a support person for a victim before or during a conference. This exposure seemed to reassure them that RJ had potential for victims. By comparison, just one of the Queensland participants had had direct exposure to RJ. During the interviews, the South Australian participants often drew on their experiences with RJ practices to talk about the real benefits and concerns for victims. One advocate 19 described a conference she had attended for a sexual assault case, saying, ?if a conference is done properly, it is a way more powerful tool [than going to court]? (SA3). The Queensland advocates spoke from a position of principle rather than experience, as indicated by an advocate who said, ?I think it would be an absolute nightmare, I can?t even begin to think of what it would look like for it to work? (QLD5). RJ as an Alternative to Criminal Justice Almost all the advocates cited some beneficial elements of RJ processes for gendered violence. One of the most frequently mentioned benefits was that RJ provided a clear alternative to the criminal justice system. As one advocate stated: The main benefit I see is that it provides an alternative to the existing system ? The existing system, which is an adversarial system, isn?t working for victims of intimate violence. (SA5) The advocates? conceptualization of RJ as an activity distinct from the justice system is not surprising given their deeply felt frustrations with established justice responses to gendered violence. One advocate whose core work is to support victims going through the criminal process said this about RJ?s benefits: Not having to go through the criminal justice system is a huge benefit. It?s so demoralizing and judging, and it sets up this win-lose situation ... With the criminal justice system, there isn?t anything around rehabilitation, any focus on repairing the situation. There is such loss in the criminal justice system. (SA8) Not all of the advocates, however, felt that RJ should be viewed as an alternative to existing criminal justice. Several believed that RJ may be most effective as a parallel process to established criminal proceedings, thereby retaining the sanctioning clout of a court process and providing a forum for victims to express themselves and to be heard. One advocate said, ?I would still be an advocate for conferencing to be used in the context of sentencing processes, I think, not necessarily as an alternative 20 to going to court? (SA5), and another stated, ?In cases of intimate violence, [RJ] should exist not as an alternative, but as ? a service or a process available, either now or any time in the future, in the course of [the victim?s] own healing? (SA4). The relative informality of RJ was also seen to be beneficial for victims, and in particular those who wished to maintain relationships with an offender or for young victims. One advocate reflected on this positive aspect of RJ: One of the advantages of restorative justice [is that] it is a different way to think about things, and therefore an opportunity for more innovative responses ? That might appeal to victims who report or disclose their victimization for the purpose of trying to stop it, but they don?t want to see their partner or their family member being dragged into a court process. What they want is for that person to be dealt with in a fashion that stops the violence and allows the relationship to continue ? So therefore we stretch the range of alternatives that are offered to victims of crime. (SA1) The Victim?s Voice The importance of the victim?s voice and the opportunity to speak about her experience was a recurrent theme in the interviews. Advocates see the potential for RJ processes to give victims a chance to speak and to be heard in a way that the criminal court does not allow. RJ may also empower victims to participate in decision-making and to propose desired outcomes. The healing opportunity to ?confront? the offender was seen as a benefit by this advocate: We encourage people as a way of voicing it, having it said in public, a public acknowledgement that this happened, whether or not the perpetrator is found guilty or not guilty, that the perpetrator has been confronted with what they have done. And that can actually be quite therapeutic and healing for the victim. (SA3) Several advocates spoke of how RJ may be able to address power imbalances between victims and offenders, in clear opposition to the widely held feminist critique that RJ processes will exacerbate power imbalance. Two advocates said this about how RJ could contend with power: It could give women a voice in the process. It could give them a forum where the power imbalance is addressed so they can actually participate. (QLD7) Restorative justice models rely on the notion of power and the recognition that there is some way of trying to rebalance power relationships between two parties. (SA1) 21 That advocates perceive RJ as being capable of addressing power differentials constructively was a surprising finding of this study. One of the most commonly cited concerns about RJ is that power imbalances will prevent victims from being effective participants in the process (Busch, 2002). But by creating forums that privilege the victim?s voice and account of her experiences, the distribution of power between victim and offender can be rebalanced. As noted by Presser and Gaarder (2000, p. 178), ?victims who have a say in the legal proceedings may feel more empowered to get help, if not to terminate the abusive relationship.? While imbalances of power between victim and offender, and men and women, are not small matters, they need not be viewed as inherent impediments to RJ. RJ Allows Offenders to Acknowledge Responsibility In addition to the benefits that may accrue to victims, the advocates also believed that RJ could better serve offenders by lowering the stakes for acknowledging their violent behavior. Admitting guilt for an offence is a keystone of most RJ programs, and this insistence that offenders take responsibility for their behavior is an attractive feature for advocates. Victims of gendered violence often bear a deep sense of guilt and self-blame, and criminal processes can reinforce this by questioning their behavior and relationship choices (Frohmann, 1998). Furthermore, the established criminal justice system offers perpetrators little incentive for full admissions of guilt, and in fact ?defendants (or their lawyers) are making an accurate assessment of the (good) chances of acquittal? by maintaining a stance of denial (Heath & Naffine, 1994). Because RJ processes are set in motion only after an offender admits to an offence, advocates perceived greater opportunity for the healing of victims and therapeutic interventions for offenders. The following comments reflect this potential benefit of RJ: Anything that establishes the guilt of somebody in a formal, relatively public sense probably has a significant effect on how the family of the victim can manage that. (SA2) Any healing of any relationship comes from a process of restorative justice, whatever it?s called, that is, the process of someone who has been hurt being heard. That is where healing comes from, they need to be heard and they need the other person to take responsibility for what they did. (SA4) 22 Advocates know that victims of gendered violence must contend with systematic disbelief throughout the justice system. Restorative justice has the potential to recognize victims? desire for ?clear and public acknowledgement? (Martin, 1998, p. 184) by lowering the penalty stakes for offenders to take responsibility for their actions. We must be cognizant, however, that many violent men may be incapable of ?hearing and taking seriously victims? account of the impact of their offending? (Stubbs, 1997, p. 121). ?WE WOULD BE MOVING SO FAR BACKWARDS:? CONCERNS ABOUT RJ Although most advocates saw positive elements in RJ, they also expressed concerns and reservations, at times quite vigorously. For example, when one advocate was contacted to arrange an interview time, she said, ?I don?t know why you are bothering, I can tell you right now that I am completely opposed to restorative justice.? Recapitulating what we see in the academic literature, their major concerns were that RJ processes may cause victims to be re-victimized, power imbalances will be exacerbated, victims will feel pressure to choose RJ over other criminal proceedings, RJ may appear to be a ?soft option? or ?cheap justice? for victims, and RJ can re-privatize gendered violence. Re-Victimization and Imbalances of Power Eight of the 15 advocates believed that victims could be re-victimized by RJ practices, particularly if it involved a face-to-face meeting with the offender. A related concern was that power imbalances between the victim and offender would be difficult to address and manage in an informal process, as captured in this statement: It is potentially forcing a woman to be in less formal conversations with an alleged perpetrator, which I think could be more abusive than the formality of a court situation with the barriers and stuff that we?ve got there. (SA7) 23 Busch (2002), drawing from Astor (1994), provides a lucid discussion of how power imbalances may impede RJ conferences for cases of domestic violence. Facilitators may be unable or lack the skill and insight to challenge ?an abuser?s belief systems? (p. 237), an abuser may threaten the victim or others at the conference, and balancing power or equality in the conference setting may be an impossible goal in light of a history of violence. It is often remarked, moreover, that abusers can intimidate and control victims through gestures or words that may be invisible to everyone in the room except for the victim. Hence, many feminists and victim advocates (both RJ proponents and critics) would say that the informality of restorative justice processes can risk exposing victims to further violence or intimidation, compromising the integrity of the conference. We would counter this concern by noting that court processes also create risks for victims and that abusers? intimidation tactics can be carried out in both court rooms and conference settings. Further, there are ways around this problem for RJ processes; victim presence could be optional, a victim could opt to present a pre-recorded statement or to send a representative to the conference, or the victim and offender could be in separate rooms with a speaker phone system. Further, we agree with the advocates who insisted that conference coordinators be required to undergo training on the dynamics of gendered violence. If a coordinator suspected or observed signs of intimidation, threat, or abusive language, the conference could be immediately stopped or referred to court. The Cheap Justice Problem Stubbs (2002, p. 51) and other feminist scholars have suggested that ?restorative justice may be seen to be offering a form of second class justice?, and six of the 15 advocates specifically used the term ?soft option? to describe RJ. The perception of RJ as an easy option worried advocates, as reflected in these comments: My concern about shifting into a restorative justice model, I hate to use this term, but it is a soft option. My concern is that there will at least be a perception, and that might be quite an influential 24 perception, that the criminal justice system is saying somehow that [gendered violence] is different and less serious. (SA5) I think it?s a pretty cruisy way out for an offender. He?s not really paying too much of a price, he might suffer some shame and embarrassment, have to apologize in front of some people, but I think the offender is getting off reasonably lightly. (QLD3) Even the advocates who themselves believed that RJ could be a powerful intervention for gendered violence expressed the fear that RJ will appear to the public to be a too lenient response. One advocate who has worked to promote the benefits of RJ in the victim advocacy community acknowledged this dilemma: Because there is a perception, I think a widely held community perception that a family conference is a slap on the wrist ? If rape and sexual assault and domestic violence were to go to that, then maybe the community wouldn?t see them as significant, important crimes that really need to be prosecuted, you know, high crimes. They might be devalued, or the experience of those crimes might be devalued. (SA3) Kelly and Radford (1996, p. 31) have warned that diversion programs for abusive men send a powerful message that gendered violence ?is less deserving of legal sanction than other offences? and that we must guard against practices which allow for the ?privileging of men who abuse women and children.? Martin (1998, p. 155), on the other hand, argues that feminists must look beyond punitive justice as the sole mechanism for taking gendered violence seriously because criminal justice ?does little to serve the goals of equality and security?. Hudson (1998, p. 245) accurately describes this impasse when she writes: The dilemma ? is that of moving away from punitive reactions, which ? even when enforced ? further brutalize perpetrators, without, by leniency of reaction, giving the impression that sexualized ? violence is acceptable behavior. Linked with the advocates? concern that RJ could subject victims of gendered violence to ?cheap justice? is that RJ will re-privatize gendered violence after decades of work to raise social awareness and to make legal authorities and the broader community take violence against women and children seriously: 25 I think part of it is a backlash against feminism, and the increase in patriarchy in our society. The white picket fence, get back behind there with the kids, it is all part of those false family ideals. (QLD6) The fear that RJ will undo decades of work to raise consciousness about gendered violence is shared by feminist critics. As P. Martin (1996, p. 59) warns, we must ensure that RJ processes ?do not result in the decriminalisation of family violence and a return to the viewing of family violence as a private matter or ?just a domestic.?? At the same time, we may need to balance the goal of social awareness with the desires of victims themselves. A 1993 Australian Bureau of Statistics survey found that one of the most common reasons for victims not reporting sexual assault was that they felt it was a private matter (see Doyle & Barbato, 1999, p. 51). For these victims, perhaps RJ could offer a mechanism for confronting offenders without exposing themselves and their victimization to the shame of public scrutiny. RJ May Harm Offenders Strikingly, some advocates also expressed concerns about how offenders might be negatively affected by RJ processes. Two who had worked with victims for many years suggested that some victims may use RJ processes to inflict harm on offenders, as one said: Some victims are committed to remaining victims and derive a lot of their self-definition, meaning for life out of being victims, and using that as punishment. ?I have been hurt and therefore I am entitled to hurt? ? The restorative justice process is also an opportunity for someone to become an offender themselves, a victim to become an offender, to become abusive and punishing. (SA4) This statement reminds us that neither criminal justice nor RJ processes should assume ?that victims are the virtuous ?us? and the offenders the culpable ?other?? (Strang, 2001, p. 75; see also Mills, 2003). Hudson (2003, p. 187) takes this point further by suggesting that ?the (liberal) requirement that rights and interests be kept in balance is glossed over in some RJ formulations.? She points out that: [RJ] assumes a procedural model of equality between the parties in some respects?representatives of both parties, ensuring that no one dominates proceedings?but other rules deny this equality. ? [For example] ? in some schemes, offenders are not able to include as supporters people who might approve or excuse their behaviour. 26 Hudson is referring specifically to what should and should not be considered permissible in conferences dealing with gendered violence. Although she does not ?want to promote racist, sexist or otherwise anti-social behaviour,? she argues that RJ ?should abandon [its claim to] even-handedness? by ?defin[ing] itself more clearly as victim-centred reparative justice? (p. 187). ?SOME SORT OF ACCOUNTABILITY:? WAYS FORWARD Throughout the interviews, many of the advocates reflected on ?what victims really want? when engaging a legal process. While about half said that some victims want to see the offender punished, a similar number said that victims are motivated by a more abstract sense of justice and the desire for accountability on behalf of the offender. The advocates had this to say about what victims most want: Well, women are seeking justice. They are looking for some sort of accountability and particularly want the offenders to stop offending. They are fearful that they are offending against others, and I?d say that would be more a priority for them even than their own sense of justice. Often, though, they do want to be at least acknowledged and for there to be some consequences. (QLD 4) I think there is a sense of justice that people have ? And because it is a violation, victims do have the desire that justice occurs and that the violation is to some small degree redressed. (SA7) That sense of acknowledgement fails in our current criminal justice system, the acknowledgement that yes, this has occurred?and [the offender] needs to take responsibility. (SA8) RJ holds significant promise in addressing the desires of victims to be heard, to have their suffering publicly acknowledged, and to hold perpetrators accountable for their behavior. We are mindful, however, of the limits to this potential. For example, Smart (1989, p. 164) warns that when feminists reform or make new law and policy, it is often administered by people ?far removed from the values and politics of the women?s movement.? Many of the advocates expressed the concern that RJ practices may fail to live up to RJ?s promise of extending benefits to victims, communities, and offenders. 27 Victim Agency and RJ Most victim advocates (nine of 15) said that victims should be given the power to decide if their case is disposed of by an RJ process, or referred to the criminal justice system. In addition, two-thirds felt that a feminist or victim advocacy organization should be involved in the process of screening cases for referral to a restorative or established justice process. The belief that RJ processes should give this particular set of victims decision-making authority poses a significant challenge to RJ. What degree of control should victims of gendered violence have, and for what kinds of decisions? A victim?s power is considerable if she is permitted to veto a referral to an RJ process because the veto has significant consequences for offenders. On the other hand, victims of intra-familial or partner violence may be pressured (by their partners or other family members) to choose RJ over criminal proceedings in order to avoid punitive outcomes. One advocate said: I suppose I would be concerned in some instances that women would feel too compassionate, you know, ?I don?t want to send him to jail.? (QLD7) Further, several advocates acknowledged that victims of gendered violence report their victimization precisely because they want the state to intervene on their behalf (see also Shapland?s [2000] discussion of the responsibilities that justice processes should and should not place on victims). Giving victims decision-making authority over how and when their case should be disposed is a responsibility that many simply do not want, as this advocate said: I don?t know to what extent we should be empowering victims to make decisions. I think that?s an incredible responsibility and one that not all victims want. (SA1) Clearly, many of the advocates felt strongly that victims of gendered violence must be given the opportunity to provide input and direction if an RJ process is used. This is understandable in that victim advocates do not want to see victims used or harmed by a legal process, and more positively, they would like to see victims ?empowered? by it. However, as Ashworth (2000, p. 196) argues, there must be a principled basis for balancing between ?personal interests of victims and the broader public interest? in an RJ process. Simply invoking ?the language of balance is a mere fudge,? Ashworth says, 28 and ignores the identification of ?reasonably clear and principled weighting of interests that come into play? (p. 196). Among many questions that arise in this complex area is the role of victims in sentencing. Ashworth argues, and we agree, that ?it would be unfair if sentences on offenders varied according to whether a particular victim is forgiving or vengeful? (p. 199) (see also Ashworth, 2002, pp. 584-88), and the same could be said for a victim?s role in decisions to divert a case from court prosecution. When is RJ Appropriate? It is important to reiterate that debates concerning RJ and gendered violence are complex because ?gendered violence? includes a wide range of violent acts and different mixes of ages and victim-offender relations, including child sexual abuse, incest, sexual assault, rape, domestic violence, and family violence (Kelly, 1988). Some of these offences and some of the victim-offender relations may be better suited to RJ processes than others. Advocates were more positive towards RJ for offences involving adolescent offenders and young victims. This is not surprising given RJ?s genesis for adolescent offending, coupled with the view that youthful offenders are more amenable and deserving of rehabilitation. Several advocates felt that intra-familial sexual violence and child sexual abuse, rather than sexual or physical violence occurring between adults, may be better suited to RJ interventions than established criminal justice. One advocate said, for example: It seems like a lot of sexual perpetrators start young, so if they can be picked up at that stage and helped to understand the consequences of their actions and on the victim, to people, it will help them stop. (QLD4) Advocates pointed out that cases with very young victims were unlikely to be prosecuted successfully, and that parents (or other family members) were often loath to report abuse because it would mean that their son (or other family member) would be charged with a criminal offence. For these types of cases, RJ was seen as a viable option that could help families respond to intra-familial sexual abuse in ways 29 that addressed traumas experienced by victims and families, as well as offenders? needs for intervention and rehabilitation. Advocates viewed RJ processes for violence between adults, and especially domestic violence, with more trepidation. Overall, they expressed their gravest reservations toward RJ for domestic violence, as compared to other forms of gendered violence. Again and again, advocates pointed out that domestic violence is a deeply entrenched pattern, and RJ is unlikely to be sufficient to change such ingrained behavior. At the same time, some felt that RJ could be a way to confront emotional and verbal abuse, which is difficult to prove in a criminal context. In addition, it was frequently noted that victims of domestic violence may not want their case to go to court, either out of fear of reprisal or because they intend to remain in the relationship. For these cases, advocates felt that RJ could provide an important legal response without the attendant costs (in victims? minds) associated with established criminal processes. Beyond Either/Or The advocates interviewed for this study did not see RJ merely in theoretical terms. Throughout the interviews they offered a variety of ideas about how RJ could work in concrete, operational ways. The most recognized face of RJ in Australia and New Zealand is youth justice conferencing, but the advocates recognized that RJ is a flexible concept that can take other forms and occur at other sites within the justice system. For example, it was suggested that RJ could be integrated into the existing criminal justice system, by providing mechanisms for pre-sentencing advice to judicial officials, post-sentencing ?victim impact? meetings, or pre-release conferences. These forums would give victims the benefits of RJ, including the opportunity for a victim to voice her story, to have the harm publicly acknowledged, and to hold the offender accountable for the offence, while also allowing for concurrent criminal justice processes. As pointed out by Daly (2002a), a clear view of restorative justice is impeded by the impulse of its critics ? and some supporters ? to hold it in opposition to 30 retributive justice. The advocates in this study understand Mills? (2003, p. 27) warning that ?one glove does not fit all hands? when it comes to justice policy for gendered violence. Criminal and restorative justice need not be pitted against each other as mutually exclusive ways of doing justice. Perhaps one way forward is for feminists to identify the potential and limits of each form of justice to create policy and practice that is responsive to the needs identified by victims and advocates. CONCLUSION The victim advocates interviewed for this study recognized that the current criminal justice system ?encourage[s] women to report rape and to participate in rape prosecutions that are in fact damaging to them personally? (Heath & Naffine, 1994, p. 51). Perhaps it was this disillusionment with the justice system that facilitated the advocates? openness to RJ. At the same time, the advocates clearly did not want to relinquish their reliance on criminal law, even while recognizing its patriarchal basis and systematic inadequacies. For example, early in the interview, one advocate said, ?The criminal justice system is based on patriarchy ? It is a system that fails from the beginning? It is a system that doesn?t believe women and children from the outset.? Yet, this same advocate concluded the interview by saying, ?First and foremost, sexual assault is a crime, and it needs to be dealt with in that way before any kind of restorative justice? (QLD5). As long as advocates and other feminist critics view RJ in opposition to established criminal justice, it will be perceived as a ?soft option? that is incapable of dealing with serious crimes like gendered violence. The task ahead is to create a dialogue that moves beyond this dualistic debate and seeks to imagine how the future of RJ may be shaped by feminist engagement (see also Frederick and Lizdas, 2003). In their analysis of different feminist orientations to law and violence and against women, Lewis et al. (2001, pp. 116-17) suggest the futility of taking an either/or approach. They propose that we should not choose between civil or criminal law, but rather find elements in both systems that may be useful. Nor must we choose between being a member of the feminist engagement with law camp 31 (reformists) or the critique of law?s futility camp (abstentionists). Their call to avoid ?dualistic thinking? (p. 117) comes to a halt, however, when they consider the appropriateness of RJ for domestic violence: Community conferences are absolutely inappropriate for domestic violence offences [although they] may be a positive development for some offences, for example, juvenile offences ? (p. 118). Just as some of the advocates interviewed in this study viewed RJ as a practice distinct from criminal justice, Lewis et al. understand RJ conferences as ?working outside the confines of the current legal system? (p. 118). This assessment is inaccurate for Australia and New Zealand, where conferences are an integrated component of the criminal justice system. By incorporating RJ processes into the criminal justice framework, we will increase opportunities for violent men to acknowledge responsibility for their behavior in a forum that is both legally and emotionally significant. This acknowledgement is the first step for offenders to change and for victims to recover from the offence and to rebuild their lives. It is an exciting call to action for RJ critics and supporters that most victim advocates we interviewed in South Australia and Queensland did not engage in dualistic thinking. They saw the importance of engaging with established criminal justice, while at the same time, they were open to alternatives and parallel processes that may better serve diverse groups of victims. Few advocates were willing to rule out RJ as an option for gendered violence, although most were hesitant to support its application for adult partner violence. Our study challenges the impulse of some to caricature feminists and victim advocates as supportive of strictly punitive approaches to gendered violence. The debate must move beyond either/or analyses that unequivocally promote or denigrate RJ approaches to gendered violence. We require a more flexible, pragmatic approach, which permits consideration of when RJ may (or may not) be appropriate, for which kinds of offences and victim-offender relations, and when it should be used as diversion from court or as a parallel court process. We cannot afford to put anything off the agenda. 32 REFERENCES Ashworth, A. (2000). Victims? rights, defendants? rights, and criminal procedure. In A. Crawford & J. Goodey (Eds.), Integrating a victim perspective within criminal justice: International debates (pp. 185-204). Aldershot: Ashgate/Dartmouth. Ashworth, A. (2002). Responsibilities, rights and restorative justice. British Journal of Criminology, 42, 578-595. Astor, H. (1991). Mediation and violence against women. Paper prepared for the National Committee on Violence Against Women. Report available from Violence against Women and Legal Matters Section of the Office of the Status of Women, Department of the Prime Minister and Cabinet, 3-5 National Circuit, Barton, ACT. Astor, H. (1994). Swimming against the tide: Keeping violent men out of mediation. In J. Stubbs (Ed.), Women, male violence, and the law (pp. 147-173). Sydney: The Institute of Criminology Monograph Series. Blagg, H. (2002). Restorative justice and aboriginal family: Opening a space for healing. In H. Strang & J. Braithwaite (Eds.), Restorative justice and family violence (pp. 191-205). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Bottoms, A. (2003). Some sociological reflections on restorative justice. In A. von Hirsch, J. Roberts, A. E. Bottoms, K. Roach, & M. Schiff (Eds.), Restorative justice and criminal justice: Competing or reconcilable paradigms? (pp. 79-114). Oxford: Hart Publishing. Braithwaite, J. (1999). Restorative justice: assessing optimistic and pessimistic accounts. In M. Tonry (Ed.), Crime and justice: A review of research, Vol. 25 (pp. 1-127). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Braithwaite, J., & Daly, K. (1994). Masculinities, violence and communitarian control. In T. Newburn & E. A. Stanko (Eds.), Just boys doing business? Men, masculinities, and crime (pp. 189-213). London: Routledge. 33 Busch, R. (2002). Domestic violence and restorative justice initiatives: Who pays if we get it wrong? In H. Strang & J. Braithwaite (Eds.), Restorative justice and family violence (pp. 223-248). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Centre Against Sexual Assault (1997). Just tokens? A report on the experience of victim/survivors of sexual assault when making application for crimes compensation. Carlton, Vic: Centre Against Sexual Violence, Royal Women?s Hospital. Cobb, S. (1997). The domestication of violence in mediation. Law & Society Review, 31, 397-440. Coker, D. (1999). Enhancing autonomy for battered women: Lessons from Navajo peacemaking. UCLA Law Review, 47, 1-111. Coker, D. (2002). Transformative justice: Anti-subordination processes in cases of domestic violence. In H. Strang & J. Braithwaite (Eds.), Restorative justice and family violence (pp. 128-152). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Cook, B., David, F., & Grant, A. (2001). Sexual violence in Australia. Canberra, ACT: Australian Institute of Criminology Research and Public Policy Series. Crawford, A., & Newburn, T. (2003). Youth offending and restorative justice: Implementing reform in youth justice. Devon, England: Willan Publishing. Daly, K. (2002a). Sexual assault and restorative justice. In H. Strang & J. Braithwaite (Eds.), Restorative justice and family violence (pp. 62-88). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Daly, K. (2002b). Restorative justice: The real story. Punishment & Society, 4, pp. 55-79. Daly, K., Curtis-Fawley, S., & Bouhours, B. (2003). Sexual offence cases finalised in court, by conference, and by formal caution in South Australia for young offenders, 1995-2001: Final report, August 2003. Brisbane: School of Criminology and Criminal Justice, Griffith University. Available at http://www.gu.edu.au/school/ccj/kdaly.html Daly, K., & Hayes, H. (2001). Restorative justice and conferencing in Australia. Trends and Issues in Crime and Criminal Justice, 186. Canberra: Australian Institute of Criminology. 34 Daly, K., & Immarigeon, R. (1998). The past, present, and future of restorative justice: Some critical reflections. The Contemporary Justice Review, 1, 21-45. Douglas, H., & Godden, L. (2002). The decriminalisation of domestic violence. Brisbane: Griffith University, The Socio-Legal Research Centre. Doyle, S., & Barbato, C. (1999). Justice delayed is justice denied: The experiences of women in court as victims of sexual assault. In J. Breckenridge & L. Laing (Eds.), Challenging silence: Innovative responses to sexual and domestic violence (pp. 47-58). St. Leonards: Allen & Unwin. Eastwood, C. (2003). The experiences of child complainants of sexual abuse in the criminal justice system. Trends and Issues in Crime and Criminal Justice, 250. Canberra: Australian Institute of Criminology. Esteal, P. (1998). Balancing the scales: Rape, law reform and Australian culture. Leichhardt, NSW: The Federation Press. Estrich, S. (1986). Rape. The Yale Law Journal, 95, 1087-1184. Fraser, N. (1989). Unruly practices: Power, discourse, and gender in contemporary social theory. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Frederick, L., & Lizdas, K. (2003). The role of restorative justice in the battered women?s movement. Battered Women?s Justice Project. Frohmann, L. (1998). Constituting power in sexual assault cases: Prosecutorial strategies for victim management. Social Problems, 45, 393-408. Frohmann, L., & Mertz, E. (1995). Legal reform and social construction: Violence, gender, and the law. Law and Social Inquiry, 20, 829-851. Goel, R. (2000). No women at the center: The use of Canadian sentencing circles in domestic violence cases. Wisconsin Women?s Law Journal, 15, 293-334. 35 Heath, M., & Naffine, N. (1994). Men?s needs and women?s desires: Feminist dilemmas about rape law ?reform.? The Australian Feminist Law Journal, 3, 30-52. Hengehold, L. (2000). Remapping the event: Institutional discourses and the trauma of rape. Signs, 26, 189-214. Holder, R. (2001). Domestic and family violence: criminal justice interventions. Australian Domestic & Family Violence Clearinghouse Issues Paper 3. Sydney: University of New South Wales. Hooper, S., & Busch, R. (1996). Domestic violence and the restorative justice initiatives: The risks of a new panacea. Waikato Law Review, 4, 101-30. Hopkins, C. Q., Koss, M., & Bachar, K. (2004). Restorative justice and sex offences: A challenge for feminist theory. Violence Against Women, this volume. Hudson, B. (1998). Restorative justice: The challenge of sexual and racial violence. Law and Society, 25, 237-256. Hudson, B. (2002). Restorative justice and gendered violence: Diversion or effective justice? British Journal of Criminology, 42, 616-634. Hudson, B. (2003). Victims and offenders. In A. von Hirsch, J. Roberts, A. E. Bottoms, K. Roach, & M. Schiff (Eds.), Restorative justice and criminal justice: Competing or reconcilable paradigms? (pp. 177-194). Oxford: Hart Publishing Johnstone, G. (2002). Restorative justice: Ideas, values, debates. Devon, England: Willan Publishing. Kelly, L. (1988). Surviving sexual violence. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Kelly, L., & Radford, J. (1996). ?Nothing really happened?: The invalidation of women?s experiences of sexual violence. In M. Hester, L. Kelly, & J. Radford (Eds.), Women, violence, and male power (pp. 19-33). Buckingham: Open University Press. Koss, M. (2000). Blame, shame, and community: Justice responses to violence against women. American Psychologist, 55, 1332-1343. 36 Kurki, L. (2000). Restorative and community justice in the United States. In M. Tonry (Ed.), Crime and justice: A review of research, Vol. 27 (pp. 235-303). Chicago: University of Chicago. Laing, L. (2002). Responding to men who perpetrate domestic violence: Controversies, interventions, and challenges. Australian Domestic & Family Violence Clearinghouse Issues Paper 7. Sydney: University of New South Wales. Laster, K., & Erez, E. (2000). The Oprah dilemma: The use and abuse of victims. In D. Chappell & P. Wilson (Eds.), Crime and criminal justice in Australia: 2000 and beyond (pp. 240-258). Sydney: Butterworths. Lewis, R., Dobash, R., Dobash, R., & Cavanagh, K. (2001). Law?s progressive potential: The value of engagement with the law for domestic violence. Social and Legal Studies, 10, 105-130. Martin, D.L. (1998). Retribution revisited: A reconsideration of feminist criminal law reform strategies. Osgoode Hall Law Journal, 36, 151-188. Martin, P. (1996). Restorative justice: A family violence perspective. Social Policy Journal of New Zealand, 6, 56-68. Maxwell, G., & Morris, A. (1993). Family, Victims and Culture: Youth Justice in New Zealand. Wellington: Institute of Criminology, Victoria University of New Zealand. McGillivray, A., & Comaskey, B. (1999). Black eyes all of the time. Toronto: University of Toronto Press. Mills, L. (2003). Insult to Injury: Rethinking our Responses to Intimate Abuse. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Mills, L. (1999). Killing her softly: Intimate abuse and the violence of state intervention. Harvard Law Review, 113, 550-613. Morris, A. (2002a). Children and family violence: Restorative messages from New Zealand. In H. Strang & J. Braithwaite (Eds.), Restorative justice and family violence (pp. 89-107). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 37 Morris, A. (2002b). Critiquing the critics: A brief response to critics of restorative justice. British Journal of Criminology, 42, 596-615. Morris, A., & Gelsthorpe, L. (2000). Re-visioning men?s violence against female partners. The Howard Journal of Criminal Justice, 39, 412-428. Morris, A., & Young, W. (2000). Reforming criminal justice: The potential of restorative justice. In H. Strang & J. Braithwaite (Eds.), Restorative justice philosophy and practice (pp. 11-31). Burlington: Ashgate. New South Wales Department for Women (1996). Heroines of fortitude: The experiences of women in court as victims of sexual assault. Woolloomooloo, NSW: NSW Department for Women. Pennell, J., & Burford, G. (2002). Feminist praxis: Making family group conferencing work. In H. Strang & J. Braithwaite (Eds.), Restorative justice and family violence (pp. 108-127). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Presser, L., & Gaarder, E. (2000). Can restorative justice reduce battering? Some preliminary considerations. Social Justice, 27, 175-194. Shapland, J. (2000). Victims and criminal justice: Creating responsible criminal justice agencies. In A. Crawford & J. Goodey (Eds.), Integrating a victim perspective within criminal justice (pp. 147-164). Smart, C. (1989). Feminism and the power of law. London: Routledge. Snider, L. (1998). Towards safer societies: Punishment, masculinities and violence against women. British Journal of Criminology, 38, 1-39. Spohn, C., & Horney, J. (1992). Rape law reform. New York: Plenum Press. Strang, H. (2001). The crime victim movement as a force in civil society. In H. Strang & J. Braithwaite (Eds.), Restorative justice and civil society (pp. 69-82). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 38 Strang, H. (2002). Repair or revenge: Victims and restorative justice. London: Oxford University Press. Strang, H., & Braithwaite, J. (2002). Restorative justice and family violence. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Stubbs, J. (1995). Communitarian conferencing and violence against women: A cautionary note. In M. Valverde, L. MacLeon, & K. Johnson (Eds.), Wife assault and the Canadian criminal justice system (pp. 260-289). Toronto: Centre of Criminology, University of Toronto. Stubbs, J. (1997). Shame, defiance, and violence against women. In S. Cook & J. Bessant (Eds.), Women?s encounters with violence: Australian experiences (pp. 109-126). London: Sage. Stubbs, J. (2002). Domestic violence and women?s safety: Feminist challenges to restorative justice. In H. Strang & J. Braithwaite (Eds.), Restorative justice and family violence (pp. 42-61). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 39 APPENDIX 1 Victim Advocacy Organizations Interviewed South Australia Women's Legal Service, Inc. Child Protective Services, Women & Children?s Hospital Victim Support Service Witness Assistance, DPP Yarrow Place Rape & Sexual Assault Service South Australia Office for the Status of Women Domestic Violence Crisis Service Victims of Crime Coordinator, Office of the Attorney General Queensland Centre Against Sexual Violence Queensland Police, Sexual Crimes Unit Gold Coast Domestic Violence Service Domestic Violence Resource Centre Coordinated Community Response to Domestic Violence Brisbane Rape and Incest Survivor's Support Centre Women's Legal Aid 40 BIOGRAPHICAL STATEMENTS Sarah Curtis-Fawley received her BA in Psychology and Women's Studies from the University of Virginia (1999), where she was deeply involved in anti- sexual assault and domestic violence advocacy work. After working on a MacArthur Foundation study on adolescent offenders' competence to stand trial (1999-01), Curtis-Fawley came to Australia as a Fulbright scholar to collaborate with Daly on the South Australia Juvenile Justice and Criminal Justice (SAJJ-CJ) project during 2001-02. Currently Curtis-Fawley works at a service for homeless youth in Adelaide. Kathleen Daly is Associate Professor, School of Criminology and Criminal Justice, Griffith University, Brisbane. She has written extensively on race and gender in crime and justice, feminism and criminology, and restorative justice. She is currently directing the South Australia Juvenile Justice and Criminal Justice (SAJJ-CJ) project, which is analysing the race and gender politics of restorative justice and indigenous justice, with a series of studies in South Australia, Queensland, and New Zealand (2001-03). She directed a major project on conferencing for youthful offenders and victims in South Australia (1998-99). work_fvwyc5ws4ngdxio64uygengy5i ---- Hot Spots Regulation and Environmental Justice Hot Spots Regulation and Environmental Justice Rama Mohana R. Turagaa, Douglas Noonanb, Ann Bostromc a Indian Institute of Management, Ahmedabad, India b School of Public Policy, Georgia Institute of Technology, Atlanta, GA c Daniel J. Evan School of Public Affairs, University of Washington, Seattle, WA Accepted manuscript; final version published as: Turaga, R. M. R., Noonan, D., & Bostrom, A. (2011). Hot spots regulation and environmental justice. Ecological Economics, 70(7), 1395–1405. doi:10.1016/j.ecolecon.2011.02.016 Corresponding Author: Rama Mohana R Turaga Public Systems Group, Indian Institute of Management Campus, Vastrapur, Ahmedabad Gujarat 380015, India Tel: +91-79-66324956 mohant@iimahd.ernet.in 2 Abstract This paper analyzes whether regulating “hot spots” of toxic air pollution by increasing the spatial resolution of regulation could address environmental justice (EJ) concerns. To examine this question, this paper develops a decision model of a regulator choosing emission controls within a net cost minimizing framework. An empirical application of the model using air toxic emission data for Escambia and Santa Rosa Counties in Florida estimates the emission standards and spatial distribution of risks at a coarse and a finer spatial resolutions. Implications for EJ are analyzed by combining the simulated spatial risk distributions at the two resolutions with the demographic data. Results indicate that different measures of EJ point to different conclusions regarding the question of whether finer resolution regulation alleviates EJ concerns. The paper concludes with a discussion of the implications for EJ policy. Keywords: environmental justice, air toxics, spatial resolution 3 1.0 Introduction Environmental justice (EJ) has been one of the central themes of environmental policy debate in the United States over the past decade. The evidence of disproportionate distribution of environmental risks and grassroots political activism in a number of communities across the country led to several policy initiatives to address EJ, including an executive order in 1992 (Brulle and Pellow, 2006). In this paper, we present an ex ante analysis of a specific policy approach primarily aimed at addressing the EJ concerns arising from emissions of air toxics.1 The policy approach studied here involves regulation at the local or community scale by characterizing air toxics risks at fine spatial resolutions. Our primary research question is: does spatially finely resolved regulation of toxic air pollutants lead to a more equitable distribution of risks? To address this question, we first develop a decision model of a net cost minimizing regulator and analyze the implications of finer resolution regulation to emission standards. We then apply the model to air toxics data in two counties to simulate how emission standards, spatial distribution of risks, and measures of EJ could change as regulation changes from a coarse spatial resolution to a finer resolution. We show that the evidence of policy effectiveness in addressing EJ concerns depends on the measure of EJ employed. Our analysis also suggests that EJ policies, in order to be effective, require a clear articulation of the goals of EJ and explicit incorporation of those goals into the decision making process of agencies. This study contributes to the growing literature on the analysis of EJ policy effectiveness. 1 Air toxics are one class of air pollutants regulated under the Clean Air Act. These include pollutants such as benzene, formaldehyde, and heavy metals. 4 This paper is organized as follows. The next sub-section reviews previous research on the evaluation of EJ policies. Section 2 presents some background on the policy approach our paper analyzes. In Section 3, we formulate our research question and describe the methodology used to test our research question. Sections 4, 5, and 6, respectively, present our decision model, empirical analyses, and results. The paper concludes in Section 7 with a brief discussion of the implications of our study for EJ policy. 1.1 Previous Research Some of the early studies on the analysis of EJ policy have focused on evaluating the impact of the EJ executive order (EJEO) 12898 on agency rule making. Bass (1998) utilized two case studies of EJ assessments under the National Environmental Policy Act (NEPA) to recommend “questions” that the federal agencies should address in assessing the EJ implication of NEPA implementation. The U.S. Government Accounting Office, in its recent reports, analyzed three air quality rules promulgated by the U.S. Environmental Protection Agency (EPA) and found that EPA is lacking in clear guidance and tools to effectively incorporate EJEO in its rulemaking (GAO, July, 2005). A more recent study analyzed the Superfund site listing before and after the EJEO and concluded that the implementation of EJEO did not address the inequity in the listing of Superfund sites (O’Neil, 2007). For example, for Superfund sites discovered after the EJEO, ceteris paribus, the probability of listing in a minority or poor community is lower, compared to the sites discovered before the EJEO. The other prominent federal program aimed at addressing EJ has been the EJ Small Grants (EJSG) Program, the objective of which is to encourage collaborative local solutions to environmental problems in EJ communities. This program funds specific non-profit 5 organizations, city, township or county governments, and Native American tribal governments involved in working with EJ communities.2 A spatial analysis of this program showed that funds under this program might not be reaching the intended communities and in several counties that received these grants, TRI emissions have actually increased (Vajjhala, 2007). Although TRI emissions represent an imperfect measure of the environmental outcomes intended under the program, this analysis suggests a lack of clarity in the criteria set for funding under the program. In addition to federal policies, several states adopt and implement EJ policies, either on their own or by federal mandates (see Ringquist and Clark, 1999 for a review of state EJ policies). A comprehensive study of state EJ policy adoption tested whether EJ policy at state level represents a protective regulatory policy or a redistributive policy and found that state EJ policies share the characteristics of both policies (Ringquist and Clark, 2002). One of the several findings of this study is that “environmental justice exists in the policy making arena as a shadow rather than as an issue of substance and immediacy” (p: 380). The authors attribute this to the lack of consensus on part of the EJ activist community on such basic issues as the nature of EJ problem and potential solutions to the problem. Finally, an important component of EJ policy is providing opportunities and avenues for the involvement of EJ communities in the decision making process. A growing trend in this area is the community-based participatory research, which emphasizes “involving community members in identifying issues in need of investigation, collaborating in the conduct of the research, and translating research-based findings into action, including advocacy for policy level change” (Petersen et al., 2006, p: 339). Case study evaluation of some of these efforts, 2 EPA Factsheet available at http://www.epa.gov/compliance/resources/publications/ej/factsheets/fact-sheet-ej- small-grants-4-08.pdf 6 especially in California, suggests significant success in the ability of these community-academic partnerships to affect policy change that benefits public health (Petersen et al., 2006; Minkler et al., 2008). The drawback of these case study evaluations is the difficulty in separating the effect of the partnerships from other contextual factors that contribute to the policy change. Overall, our review suggests that much of the emphasis in the literature has been on the “process” aspects of the EJ policy implementation (e.g., whether the EJ intervention led to a policy change and whether the adopted EJ policies are protective or redistributive in nature). Few studies analyze particular EJ policies from the perspective of the environmental outcomes to the targeted EJ groups. Further, it appears that the effectiveness of EJ policies is impeded by a lack of clarity and agreement on fundamental issues, including the nature of the EJ problem and metrics to assess “justice” or “equity” or “disproportionate impact” (Noonan, 2008). This paper addresses these issues and contributes to the EJ policy literature by analyzing, ex ante, the EJ implications of a specific policy: regulation of air toxics hot spots at fine spatial resolutions. 2.0 Policy Background The increasing use of emissions trading programs in U.S. air pollution policy has brought air pollution “hot spots” 3 – locations with unacceptably high pollutant concentrations – into focus in recent policy debates. The critics of the trading programs raise the concern that such a policy would result in hot spots near those sources for which it is cheaper to buy permits than abate emissions (e.g., Heinzerling and Steinzor, 2004). Concern about hot spots has been a 3 The National Academies study on future air quality management in the United States defined hot spots as “locales where pollutant concentrations are substantially higher than concentrations indicated by ambient outdoor monitors located in adjacent or surrounding areas (NRC, 2004, p:274).” 7 driving force of opposition, for example, to EPA’s mercury rule (Graham, 2007) and California’s greenhouse emissions regulation (Hanemann, 2008). In addition to concerns related to trading programs, there is also growing evidence of hot spots near roadways due to vehicular air pollution. Zhu et al., (2002), for example, show that the concentration of ultrafine particles within 100m of a roadway could be 25 times higher than concentrations beyond 300m. Addressing hot spots is one of the main challenges facing air quality management in the United States (NRC, 2004). 2.1 Hot Spots and Air Toxics Hot spots with regards to air toxics have been a particular concern for at least three reasons. First, air toxics emissions from a large number of small sources such as dry cleaners and gas stations have the potential to create high localized concentration of emissions in densely populated areas (EPA, 2006a). Second, the sparse ambient monitoring network4 for air toxics is unlikely to capture local variations in pollutant concentrations, especially the concentrations close to the emitting sources. Finally, evidence suggests that some population groups (low- income and minority) may be disproportionately subjected to higher risks from air toxics (e.g., see Morello-Frosch et al., 2001; Dolinoy and Miranda, 2004; Apelberg et al., 2005). 2.2 Hot Spots Regulation at Fine Spatial Resolutions Reduction of risks from hot spots has been an important component of EPA’s overall air toxics strategy. The National Air Toxics Program or “Urban Air Toxics Strategy” (EPA, 2000) intended to “characterize exposure and risk distributions….” in “geographic ’hot spots’…” (p: 38712) to achieve the goal of addressing disproportionate impacts of air toxics. Similarly, risk 4 The current national monitoring network for air toxics, called the National Air Toxics Trends Station network, has only 22 monitors across the country and monitors 18 toxic air pollutants (E.P.A, 2004), mainly in large urban areas. 8 reduction in hot spots is a “near-source” and “community/neighborhood” goal of EPA’s Workplan for the National Air Toxics Program and Integrated Air Toxics State/Local/Tribal Program Structure (EPA, 2001). One approach to deal with hot spots has been to encourage local/community-scale regulation of air toxics at fine spatial resolutions. The rationale behind this approach is that monitoring networks and modeling studies at the national scale (e.g., the National Air Toxics Assessment, which estimates risks at census tract resolution) do not provide adequate spatial resolution to regulate locations of high air toxics concentrations (i.e., hot spots) (e.g., see Dolinoy and Miranda, 2004). Thus, in its latest national air toxics monitoring strategy, instead of expanding the sparse national air toxics monitoring network, EPA decided to use 60% of its monitoring budget to fund community-scale air toxics efforts (EPA, 2004a). These projects typically involve extensive ambient monitoring or modeling studies to characterize air toxics risks at very fine spatial resolutions. Currently, EPA is supporting projects in about 30 communities across the country, under its community-based air toxics projects program.5 Consistent with this approach, EPA has also been developing tools and guidance to model air toxics risks at finely resolved spatial units. An example of this is the recently developed integrated risk assessment tool, the Regional Air Impact Modeling Initiative (RAIMI) (EPA, 2006b). RAIMI is a GIS-based tool that can be used to estimate cancer and non-cancer risks from multiple air toxics emitted from multiple sources at a community resolution. EPA has also published a detailed guidance document for conducting community-scale risk assessments as part of its Air Toxics Risk Assessment Reference Library series (EPA, 2006a). 5 http://www.epa.gov/air/toxicair/community/basic.html. Last accessed on July 8, 2009. http://www.epa.gov/air/toxicair/community/basic.html 9 An example of this policy approach is the Strategic Toxic Air Reduction (STAR) program of The Louisville Metro Air Pollution Control District Board.6 Based on extensive local monitoring and modeling studies, this program identified 37 stationary source air toxics that pose or may pose risks above a specified health risk goal; nearly 170 facilities are subject to regulation under this program. These facilities must conduct risk assessments to estimate cancer and non-cancer risks posed by their emissions and submit an emission reduction plan to reduce the risks below the health risk goal (Williams, 2007). The U.S. EPA provided financial and technical assistance to design the STAR program. 3.0 Research Question and Methodology As the discussion above illustrates, regulation at finely resolved spatial units is emerging as one of the key approaches to addressing air toxics hot spots. To elucidate the implications thereof, this paper asks: what effects will regulating air toxics at finely resolved spatial units have on the spatial distribution of risks and on environmental justice? The initial steps of our analysis strategy involve simulating spatial distribution of air toxics risks under regulation at different spatial resolutions. We then assess if and how measures of EJ change as the spatial resolution of regulation increases. The following outlines the methodology we adopt to address our research question: • We first develop a model of an optimizing decision maker within the context of air toxics regulation, based on previous research and the decision processes described by EPA and state environmental agencies. 6 http://www.louisvilleky.gov/APCD/STAR/. Last accessed on October 16, 2009. http://www.louisvilleky.gov/APCD/STAR/ 10 • We then apply this decision model to analyze stationary sources emitting air toxics in Escambia and Santa Rosa counties in Florida. The empirical analysis includes, estimation of: (i) the emission standards a regulator would set and (ii) the resulting spatial distribution of risks under two spatial resolutions of regulation: the census tract and a finer census block resolution. This simulates the risk distribution that would result from a policy aimed at addressing hot spots (i.e., regulation at finer resolution). • Lastly, we overlay the spatial distributions of risk estimated at each resolution (in the previous step) on to the demographic data in our study area to analyze the EJ implications of spatially finely resolved regulation. We use three different measures of EJ, explained in the later sections. 4.0 A Model of Air Toxics Decision Making The predominant policy tool employed in the management of air toxics in the U.S. is emission standards, which either limit the emissions to a specified level or specify the technology that the regulated entities should employ to control emissions. In order to develop our decision making model, we review the relevant federal and state level regulations. A key element of consideration in the risk-based regulation of air toxics is the concept of maximum individual risk (MIR). MIR is the lifetime upper-bound risk to which the maximally exposed individual would be exposed. In 1987, in its judgment in the Vinyl Chloride case, the U.S. Court of Appeals for the District of Columbia directed EPA to consider costs of air toxics regulation only after ensuring an acceptable MIR. Since then, MIR has been a constraint that EPA has to meet in its decisions on setting emission standards for air toxics.7 7 van Houtven and Cropper (1996) analyzed EPA’s air toxics decisions under the Clean Air Act of 1970 and found that EPA considered both the costs and benefits of regulation until the verdict on the Vinyl Chloride case; after the 11 In its current residual risk regulations, 8 EPA adopts a two-step decision process, which is consistent with the direction of the court in the Vinyl Chloride case. The first step involves determining the acceptable MIR. The second step sets emission standards, taking into account other factors including the costs of compliance, technological feasibility, and population risks, but only after ensuring that the MIR will not exceed the acceptable level determined in the first step (EPA, 1999b). A related regulation at the state level is the Air Toxics “Hot spots” Information and Assessment Act enacted by the California Air Resources Board in 1987. This act requires that the facilities that cause “significant” health risks conduct health risk assessments and inform the affected public of those risks. “Significant” health risks are those risks that exceed the threshold risk levels set by the concerned Air Pollution Control Districts (APCD). This threshold risk is similar to MIR under the federal residual risk regulation. Facilities that exceed the threshold risk must submit a “risk audit and reduction plan” for APCD’s approval, in order to bring the risks down to the threshold value. Consistent with these decision processes and following the previous models of agency decision making in the literature,9 the regulator in our decision model chooses emission standards to minimize net costs, subject to the constraint that the MIR does not exceed a threshold level. The MIR, however, is determined as the maximum risk estimated based on a fixed number of locations in space (for example, ambient air monitoring network or the receptor network of an air quality model). Hence, we model the MIR constraint as follows: no spatial location over which risks are regulated should have a risk exceeding the threshold value. Vinyl Chloride decision, however, EPA did not consider costs in regulating air toxics, unless the estimated MIR was below 1 in 10,000. 8 Under the residual risk rules, EPA is required to assess the risks that remain after the implementation of technology standards and set additional standards, if required. 9 Such previous studies include analysis of pesticide regulations (Cropper et al., 1992), Superfund clean-up decisions (Gupta et al., 1992), and state adoptions of strict liability programs (Alberini and Austin, 1999). 12 4.1 Decision Problem Set-up Suppose there are I sources (i =1,2,…,I), each emitting J toxic air pollutants (j = 1,2,3,….,J). First, we assume that the regulator cares about only two types of costs: private costs of compliance for the polluting sources and the health costs of residual risk. We further assume for simplicity that our regulator weighs these two costs equally. For any source i reducing its emissions of pollutant j from the initial level of Qbij to Qij, and given MCij (assumed to be strictly convex and increasing) as the marginal cost function for that pollutant and source, the private abatement cost (or compliance costs) takes the form: ij b ij Q I J p ij ij ij i=1 j=1 Q C MC (Q ) dQ= ∑∑ ∫ (1) 0p ijC Q∂ ∂ < (2) The second type of costs our regulator is concerned about is the population health costs. We assume here that our regulator quantifies only the health costs associated with cancer risks and that the cancer risks are additive across different toxic pollutants. To develop an expression for these health costs, we begin with the individual cancer risk, 10 rm, defined as: 1 1 I J m ij ijm j i j r Q uβ = = = ∑∑ for all individuals m = 1,2,3,…, M (3) Where, ijQ Emission rate (gram/second) of pollutant j from i th source 10 Cancer risk is expressed as probability. For example, if the cancer risk is n in a million, then it is expected that there will be ‘n’ additional cases of cancer when a million people are exposed to that level of risk. 13 ijmβ Exposure concentration, in [( 3/g mµ )/(g/s)], an individual m is exposed to due to a unit emission rate (1 g/s) of pollutant j from source i = f (meteorology, emission and site characteristics, location of m with respect to the source, activity patterns of individuals, etc.,) ju Unit Risk Factor for j th pollutant, ( 3/g mµ )-1, which represents the probability of cancer due to continuous exposure for 70 years to 1 3/g mµ of pollutant j For M individuals (indexed m =1,2,…,M) exposed, the total population risk (i.e., the total number of expected additional cancer cases) is merely the sum of all the individual risks. Assuming that the value of statistical life (VSL) is constant across all individuals, the population health costs could be estimated simply as the product of the total number of expected additional cancer cases and the VSL (V).11 Thus, the health costs associated with cancer are given as: 1 M h m m C r V = = ∑ (4) 0h ijC Q∂ ∂ > (5) The MIR constraint requires that the maximum cancer risk not exceed the threshold value of r. Let K be spatial resolution at which risks are regulated. Here K represents the number of locations, within a geographic area of interest, over which risks are regulated. The MIR constraint for regulating risks at spatial resolution K can be expressed as: 1 1 1,2,3,…., I J ij ijk j i j Q u r k Kβ = = ≤ ∀ =∑∑ (6) 11 This assumes that incidence of cancer results in mortality and that VSL is constant across additional cancer cases. Because V enters as a scalar, it implies that there is no heterogeneity across individuals in their willingness to pay to reduce the risk of death. 14 where ijkβ is the exposure concentration due to unit emissions at any given spatial location k. K is a variable of interest for the research question addressed here. A finer spatial resolution of regulation would then mean an increase in the number of receptor locations over which risks are regulated. In other words, K is increasing with spatial resolution.12 Regulating over census tracts instead of counties, for example, implies increasing K. The decision maker’s objective function is thus: ( ) 1 1 1 1 1 . ij ij b ij QI J I J M ij ij ij ij ijm jQ i j i j mQ Min MC Q dQ Q u Vβ = = = = =                +∑∑ ∑∑∑∫ (7) subject to the constraints in equation (6) and the non-negative emissions constraints: 0≥ijQ In the next section, we apply this decision model13 to air toxics data of two counties, Escambia and Santa Rosa in Florida, to first estimate the emission standards a regulator would choose under a coarse resolution (K) and a finer resolution ( K′ >K). The emission standards under the two resolutions of regulation will then be used to estimate the resulting spatial distribution of risks at each resolution. Finally, we combine these risk estimates with demographic data to analyze the EJ implications of regulating at finer spatial resolutions. 12 Our conception of finer resolution here is simply an increase in the number of spatial locations over which risks are regulated. The implicit assumption is that the location of new receptors at the finer resolution is arbitrarily determined, which appears to be the case in the real world (Su et al., 2007). 13 The full analytical solution for the model is available from the authors. The basic result is that the optimal emission standards at finer regulation could be stricter, laxer, or unchanged relative to the emission standards at coarse regulation. The direction of change depends on (i) whether or not the finer resolution reveals new hot spots that are not revealed at coarse resolutions and (ii) how much a source/pollutant contributes to the risk at those new hot spots. The full solution is not included here due to space constraints. 15 5.0 Empirical Analysis Our study area consists of two counties in Northwest Florida: Escambia and Santa Rosa. This region has a history of problems related to toxic pollutants and environmental justice. One of the most publicized problems has been the case of “Mount Dioxin,” a Superfund site of Escambia Treating Company. The dioxin contamination from this site prompted grassroots level action and led to relocation of people living near the site (see Bullard and Johnson, 2000). More recent concerns relate to the quantities of toxics emissions. According to the toxic release inventory data of 2005, Escambia county was ranked top and Santa Rosa was ranked 9th in Florida in terms of total tons of toxics released into various media. Responding to public concerns related to environmental impacts, the US Congress sponsored the Partnership for Environmental Research and Community Health (PERCH) to conduct a series of environmental health studies, including an assessment of air toxics risks in the region (UWF, 2011). According to the National Toxics Inventory (NTI) of 1999, our study area had 94 air toxics emission sources distributed across 43 facilities, including manufacturing plants, utilities, and waste landfills, and emitting 78 different air toxics. The sources include “major” 14 sources as well as “area”15 sources. Many of these sources are currently regulated under the Maximum Achievable Control Technology (MACT) standards developed by the federal EPA under the CAA. Florida, to the best of our knowledge, does not have a separate state program that regulates the sources of air toxics. Florida department of environmental protection, however, 14 A “major” source is one that emits more than 10 tons per year (TPY) of any one of the regulated air toxics or more than 25 TPY of a combination of air toxics. 15 “Area” sources emit quantities below the thresholds specified for “major” sources. 16 issues operating permits in accordance with the federal regulations and enforces compliance with the permits. We use two criteria to select a subset of the 94 sources for our analysis: (1) the source is categorized as a “major” source and (2) the source emits at least one toxic air pollutant for which inhalation cancer risk can be quantified (because our model assumes quantification of only cancer risks). Based on these criteria, our final sample includes 15 sources from seven facilities, which emit six different air toxics.16 The empirical analysis uses three nested spatial resolutions: census tract, census block group, and census block.17 The census tract (“tract” from hereon) is the biggest spatial unit and is composed of several census block groups (“block group” from hereon) while the census block (“block” from hereon) is the finest spatial unit with a number of blocks forming a block group. Furthermore, in the empirical analysis, because it is not possible to estimate risks at the individual level, we apply the risk estimated at the geographical centroid of a census unit to all the individuals within that census unit. Finally, consistent with the theoretical decision model, in our empirical analysis, finer resolution is assumed to include all those locations over which risks would be regulated at the coarse resolution in addition to the new receptors. Thus, for example, the receptors for regulation at the block group resolution include not only the centroids of all the block groups but also that of all the census tracts. General Algebraic Modeling System (www.gams.com) version 22.3 is used to solve the optimization model. 5.1 Data 16 We dropped one facility that met our criteria from the final sample because no abatement cost information was available. 17 The choice of census unit to characterize spatial resolution is one of convenience; with the advent of advanced remote sensing technologies to characterize air pollution, it is perhaps possible to regulate at much finer resolutions than those we choose here. http://www.gams.com/ 17 5.1.1 Marginal Cost (MC) Functions We estimate marginal MC functions using an engineering cost approach, which is a common method in the literature (e.g., Kilmont et al., 2000; EPA, 2003; Karvosenoja and Johansson, 2003; Rousseau and Proost, 2005). Ideally, the MC functions should be derived for each source based on the data specific to the source. In reality, however, such information is rarely available, if ever, especially for air toxics. Thus in our case, we make some assumptions to make sense of the little that data are available. Specifically, we assume that each of the sources in our analysis represents a “typical” or “average” firm in that source category. We rely on EPA’s abatement costs estimates under its technology-based MACT standards. EPA is required to conduct Regulatory Impact Analyses (RIA) to assess the costs and benefits of its costly regulations. In case of MACT standards, the EPA assessed the costs of a range of available abatement technologies for each regulated source category. To estimate the cost functions for our empirical analysis, we first identify the MACT standards relevant to the air toxics sources in our sample. We then use the air permit documents available from the Florida Department of Environmental Protection to match our sources with the corresponding MACT standard. After identifying the relevant MACT for each source, we collect, from the relevant RIAs, the information on the emission control options including the range of control technology options available, the emission reductions associated with each technology option, and the annual costs of implementing the technology.18 The annual costs include estimated annualized capital costs as well as operational costs. Because these studies were carried out in different 18 This data on abatement technology options, removal efficiencies, and annual costs for each source are available from the authors on request. 18 years, we convert all costs into 1999$. Typically, the RIAs report total compliance cost estimates aggregated at the level of the source category. The estimates, however, report the number of firms on which these aggregate estimates are based. Thus, for an “average” firm, the estimated costs could be calculated as the total sector-wise annual costs divided by the number of firms. Based on our assumption that the source in our analysis represents an “average” source in that category, we use the cost estimates generated in the previous step for our empirical analysis In this analysis, in order to be consistent with the assumptions of our decision model (i.e., strictly convex and increasing MC functions), we fit our cost estimates to an exponential functional form. Another advantage of an exponential form for our analysis is that this functional form restricts the estimated annual costs to positive values. This is also consistent with previous studies, which assumed either a quadratic form (Hartman et al., 1997) or an exponential function (Mariam and Barre, 1996). ij ij b Q ij ij C a e= (8) Annual costs of abatement for pollutant from source ($) Emission levels of pollutant from source (Ton/Year) , Parameters to be estimated ij ij ij ij C j i Q j i a b = = = The cost function is fitted using non-linear least squares regressions with the annual costs as the dependent variable and emission level (TPY) as the independent variable. The estimated cost parameters for various sources are given in Table 1. The table also shows the standard errors for the coefficient estimates. Because the data for some sources had only two abatement technology options, the standard errors could not be estimated. 19 [TABLE 1 APPROXIMATELY HERE] 5.1.2 Exposure Concentrations ( ijmβ ) Application of the decision model to simulate the optimal emission standards a regulator would set requires estimation of exposure concentrations at the centroids of various census units. This analysis estimates the annual average ambient air toxics concentrations using the version 3 of the Industrial Source Complex Short Term (ISCST3)19 air dispersion model, integrated within RAIMI, the integrated risk assessment tool developed by EPA. RAIMI uses a geographical information system (GIS) interface. The GIS data required for RAIMI include (i) land use and land cover maps, which we obtained from Florida Geographic Data Library, (ii) digital elevation maps, which we collected from the United States Geological Survey, and (iii) aerial photographs of the two county region, downloaded from Terra Server (http://terraserver.microsoft.com). The ISCST model also requires hourly upper air and surface meteorological data. We use EPA’s Meteorological Preprocessor for Regulatory Models to process the raw meteorological data collected at the Pensacola Airport for the years 1986 to 1990. Although the theoretical model requires that we estimate the exposure concentrations, we use the ambient air toxics concentrations as surrogates for exposure concentrations because RAIMI does not incorporate an exposure model. In addition, the risk estimation within RAIMI is based on the assumption that individuals would be exposed to the same estimated exposure concentrations throughout their lifetime. This is not realistic but it is very difficult, if not impossible, to predict 19 ISCST3 is a steady-state, multiple source, Gaussian dispersion model and has been the preferred regulatory model for industrial sources until it was replaced by AMS/EPA Regulatory Model (AERMOD) in 2005 (FR, 2005) http://terraserver.microsoft.com/ 20 the lifetime exposures, which depend on the environment in which the individual will live in his/her entire lifetime. 5.1.3 Other Data With regards to the other data, we adopt a value of $5.5 million (1999$) for VSL (V in the model). This is the same value EPA used for its benefit cost assessment of the Clean Air Act (EPA, 1999a) for 1990-2010 (EPA used a mean VSL of $4.8 million in 1990$, which is $5.5 million in 1999$). The baseline emissions (Qbij in the decision model) represent current emissions according to the 1999 NTI for the sources and pollutants selected for the empirical analysis. Values of unit risk factors, ju , for each of the six pollutants in the sample are obtained from EPA’s Integrated Risk Information System database. The values used in the analysis are: 0.0000078 for benzene, 0.0000022 for acetaldehyde, 0.000013 for formaldehyde, 0.000068 for acrylonitrile, 0.00024 for nickel, and 0.0043 for arsenic. Finally, we obtain the population data from the US Census Bureau for the year 2000. 21 6.0 Results 6.1 Emission Standards Table 2 shows the estimated emission standards at three spatial resolutions under a MIR constraint of 100 in a million. The emission standards do not change at the block group resolution compared to a coarser census tract resolution. This is because regulation at block group resolution for our empirical setting does not capture any new hot spots. The last column of Table 2 shows the emission standards at the finest (block) resolution. Compared to regulation at coarser resolution, the emissions at this resolution are higher for a majority of sources and lower for some sources – resolution of regulation at the block level captured new hot spots that would not have been regulated at the coarser resolutions. Table 3 shows the estimated emission standards under different resolutions of regulation at a more restrictive threshold cancer risk of 10 in a million. [TABLE2 2 and 3 APPROXIMATELY HERE] 6.2 Spatial Distribution of Cancer Risk We use these emission standards, Q*ij, to estimate cumulative excess individual cancer risk, rb, attributable to air toxics exposures at the centroid of each census block (b=1,2,…,B) in our two-county region for each spatial resolution of regulation. By estimating risk at the centroid, we assume that each individual in the census block is exposed to that risk level. We calculate the cancer risk with the following equation (the terms are defined as before): 22 * 1 1 1,2,3,…., I J b ij ijb j i j r Q u b Bβ = = = ∀ =∑∑ (9) Figures 1 shows the spatial distribution of cancer risks when air toxics are regulated at the tract resolution with the threshold risk constraint of 100 in a million. Figure 2 shows the spatial distribution at the block resolution regulation for the same threshold risk. Figures 3 and 4 show the spatial distribution of cancer risk for tract and block regulation, respectively, at the 10 in a million risk threshold. [FIGURES 1 to 4 APPROXIMATELY HERE] 6.3 Environmental Justice Analysis The first EJ measure we use is based on an interpretation of EJ by the EPA: “Environmental Justice is the fair treatment and meaningful involvement of all people regardless of race, color, national origin, or income with respect to the development, implementation, and enforcement of environmental laws, regulations, and policies. Fair treatment means that no group of people should bear a disproportionate share of the negative environmental consequences resulting from industrial, governmental and commercial operations or policies.” (EPA, 2008) Based on this interpretation, we assess the EJ implication of regulation at finer resolution by using the following measure: EJ Measure 1: No population group should be disproportionately exposed to hot spots. 23 In this measure, the “negative environmental consequence” is the probability of an adverse health outcome, which in our case is the risk of cancer. If one defines hot spots as the locations at which the risk of an adverse health outcome is above an acceptable threshold, as we have defined in this paper, then a comparison of Figure 1 and Figure 2 shows that the regulation at finer block resolution would eliminate the hot spots that would have resulted from a coarse regulation (the blocks in black in Figure 1 are no longer seen in Figure 2). This holds true at the 10 in a million threshold risk (Figures 3 and 4) as well. The result is not surprising because at the block regulation, our decision model constrains the risk in each block to the acceptable threshold risk. Thus, by this definition of EJ, under the regulation at finer spatial resolution, no group is disproportionately exposed to unacceptable risk levels. The second measure we use is based on the “disproportionately adverse effect” definition developed by EPA in its EJ toolkit for staff. “….the term disproportionately high and adverse effects or impacts means an adverse effect or impact that: (1) is predominately borne by any segment of the population, including a minority population and/or a low-income population; or (2) will be suffered by a minority population and/or low-income population and is appreciably more severe or greater in magnitude than the adverse effect or impact that will be suffered by a non- minority population and/or non-low-income population.” (EPA, 2004b, p: 71) The toolkit also emphasizes that, to assess whether an EJ concern exists, the adverse impacts in the communities of concern should be compared to the impacts in reference communities. In our interpretation of this guidance, a “community of concern” is any census block in which the proportion of minority population is higher than the proportion of minority 24 population in our study area as a whole. The proportion of minorities in our study area is 22.4% and thus any block group that has a minority population share of more than 22.4% is a community of concern for our analysis. To assess the EJ implications, we compare the mean individual cancer risk in communities of concern to the mean individual risk in all other communities. Base on this classification, our EJ measure is: EJ Measure 2: On average, communities with a larger proportion of minorities than the region as a whole should not be exposed to greater individual cancer risks than the other communities. Table 4 shows the results of our analysis. At the tract resolution, the mean individual risk in the communities of concern is significantly higher than the mean risk in the reference communities. This is the case for both the 100 in a million and 10 in a million risk thresholds. If the regulation at finer resolution were to address the EJ concern, as defined by our measure, the difference in mean risk between the two communities should be statistically insignificant at the finer block resolution. However, as the table 4 shows, that is not the case. The mean individual cancer risk at the finer block resolution is statistically higher in the communities of concern at both the threshold risks. Thus, the regulation at finer resolutions does not address the EJ concerns, as defined by this second measure. Our third EJ measure is based on a population risk measure. The previous two measures are based on individual risk, which represents the probability that an individual will develop a cancer when exposed to a certain concentration of air toxics. The population risk is simply the 25 sum of individual risks in a population. For example, if a million people are exposed to a 1 in a million risk, the expected population risk is one case of cancer. 20 At any given resolution of regulation, we assess equity with respect to the population risk using the following measure: White, Non-white i i i i i i i CC CC EJPOP i POP POP = = ∑ ∑ (10) Where iCC = Additional Expected Cancer Cases for Racial Group i iPOP = Population of Racial Group i In a just world, each population group should have a value of one for this measure. A value greater (less) than one indicates that the group bears a greater (lower) share of the expected cancer cases relative to the share of their population. [TABLE 4 APPROXIMATELY HERE] EJ Measure 3: The share of expected additional cancer cases for minorities as a proportion of their share of total population should be equal to one. Figure 5 and Figure 6 show the results of the analysis with respect to our population risk EJ measure. Both figures show that at tract resolution as well as block resolution, the EJ 20 One can argue that the population risk is a more appropriate measure because it weights the risk by population. For example, if two census blocks are exposed to same individual risk but if one of the blocks has a much higher population than the other, the individual risk measure will not capture the fact that the overall risk is greater in the block with larger population. 26 measure is greater than one for nonwhites and less than one for whites. As explained earlier, this result indicates that nonwhites would share a greater share of expected cancer cases relative to their share of population and this situation is not alleviated at a finer resolution regulation. That is, if finer resolution regulation were to address EJ concerns, our EJ measure should reduce from greater than one at tract resolution to one at block resolution, which does not happen either at 100 in a million threshold risk scenario or at the 10 in a million risk threshold scenario. This suggests that the regulation at finer resolutions is unlikely to adequately address EJ concerns as defined by our third measure. [FIGURES 5 and 6 APPROXIMATELY HERE] 7.0 Discussion and Implications Regulation of air toxics at finely resolved spatial units has been emerging as an approach to deal with hot spots. Given that addressing EJ concerns is one of the primary rationales for regulating hot spots, our goal in this paper was to analyze, ex ante, whether the policy of finer regulation of hot spots could address EJ concerns. Based on the interpretation of various regulations and guidelines on EJ, we constructed three measures of EJ in order to evaluate the policy. Our analysis suggests that increasing the resolution of regulation could change the spatial distribution of risk in such a way that the risk in hot spots (i.e., locations with risk levels beyond some acceptable level) is mitigated; the change in the distribution of risk might not, however, translate to a more equitable distribution of risk across racial groups. In other words, 27 the policy of finer resolution regulation would be a protective regulatory policy but not a redistributive policy in a way that it addresses EJ concerns. It is possible to argue that our results are not necessarily generalizable across all situations and locations. That is, it is conceivable that under some other empirical settings, spatially finer regulation would result in redistribution of risks in a way that addresses the EJ concerns, even within our modeled decision framework. Such an outcome would, however, be a result of chance rather than design. Even assuming that redistribution of risks in a way that equalizes risks across racial groups is the goal of EJ policies (which itself is not clear), the current decision process, as reflected by our model, incorporates only a general equity constraint and has no provision that explicitly addresses EJ goals. This would, by design, ensure only a protective policy. Thus in order to guide future EJ policy, EPA and the other state agencies, in collaboration with the potentially affected EJ communities, should develop well-defined EJ goals and explicitly incorporate those goals into the decision process. For example, if the goal is redistribution of risks from the EJ groups to the other groups, then such a goal could be incorporated into the decision process by specifying location-specific constraints. One such location-specific constraint could be that locations, in which the percentage of the minorities exceeds the overall percentage of the minorities in the region, should be subjected to stricter risk threshold standard than other locations. Such a constraint is easy to incorporate into the decision framework we modeled here. The challenge, however, is to arrive at a basis for specifying the location-specific risk thresholds. What should be the risk threshold for minority areas relative to other areas in the region? This question gets complicated because of the lack of conclusive 28 evidence or guidance on the extent (quantitatively) to which EJ groups are more susceptible than other groups to exposure from air pollution (see Sexton, 1997 and Post et al., 2009 for a discussion). Another implication of our findings is that the assessment of EJ policy success could depend on the definition of EJ goals. In the context of the policy we analyzed, if the goal is to ensure that the EJ communities are not exposed to adverse environmental impacts greater than some acceptable threshold levels, then the finer regulation policy meets that goal by design. If the goal, however, is to redistribute risk such that the adverse impacts are equalized across groups, then the policy of finer resolution regulation may not help. This suggests that agencies should develop clear metrics for measuring the effectiveness of EJ policies, in addition to specifying well-defined EJ goals. Future extensions to our paper can take several paths. A potentially interesting path is to investigate the implications of our assumptions, in the decision model as well as empirical analysis, for the main findings. First is the assumption that there is no variation in susceptibility to air toxics exposures across population groups. It is straightforward to incorporate such a variation into our model and empirical analysis if concentration-response functions (cancer unit risk factors in the case of toxic air pollutants) can be specified differently for different population groups. Such subgroup-specific risk factors are currently not available21, however (Sexton, 1997; Post et al., 2009). Second, due to limitations in the abatement cost data, we used the cost functions for an “average” firm in a given source category as a proxy for source-specific cost 21 The only exception with regards to cancer risk assessment is the case of children. In its “Supplemental Guidance for Assessing Susceptibility from Early-Life Exposure to Carcinogens” the EPA recommends incorporating age dependent adjustment factors (ADAFs) in the dose-response relationships (EPA, 2005b). For example, EPA recommends an ADAF of 10 for exposures before age 2 and an ADAF of 3 for exposures between the ages 2 and 16. 29 functions. Although source-specific functions are unlikely to significantly alter our main findings, future research could use the more accurate plant-specific cost functions, if available. Third, we assumed constant VSL across individuals. Theoretical and empirical evidence in environmental economics indicates that VSL could vary with such factors as age, income, and baseline risk (Hammitt, 2000). The evidence, however, does not appear conclusive (Krupnick, 2007) and thus the current regulatory analysis continues to be based on constant VSL (EPA, 2007). In our case, we expect that a varying VSL will affect the risk distributions at coarse and finer regulation in a similar fashion. Thus a varying VSL is unlikely to change our main findings significantly because our analysis is based on the differences in risk distribution between regulation at the coarse resolution and a finer resolution. Again, it is straightforward to incorporate individual-specific VSL into our model and empirical analysis and we wish to incorporate such variations in future extensions. Acknowledgments Much of this work was carried out during Turaga’s tenure first as a graduate student at the Georgia Institute of Technology, Atlanta, GA and then as a Research Associate at Dartmouth College, Hanover, NH. We gratefully acknowledge research support from the University of West Florida (UWF) Sub Award # 2519-229-22(02). The prime award is from the U.S. EPA (Award # /x974550002-3) for the Partnership for Environmental Research and Community Health (PERCH) project. We would also like to acknowledge Mark Borsuk and two anonymous reviewers for their valuable inputs to the manuscript. 30 References Alberini, A., Austin, D., 1999. On and Off the Liability Bandwagon: Explaining State Adoptions of Strict Liability in Hazardous Waste Programs. J. Regul. Econ. 15, 41-64. Apelberg, B.J., Buckley, T.J., White, R.H., 2005. Socioeconomic and Racial Disparities in Cancer Risk from Air Toxics in Maryland. Environmental Health Perspectives 113, 693. Bass, R., 1998. Evaluating environmental justice under the national environmental policy act. Environmental Impact Assessment Review 18, 83-92. Brulle, R.J., Pellow, D.N., 2006. Environmental Justice: Human Health and Environmental Inequalities. Annual Review of Public Health 27, 103–124. Bullard, R.D., Johnson, G.S., 2000. Environmental justice: Grassroots activism and its impact on public policy decision making. Journal of Social Issues 56, 555-578. Cropper, M.L., Evans, W.N., Berardi, S.J., Ducla-Soares, M.M., Portney, P.R., 1992. The Determinants of Pesticide Regulation: A Statistical Analysis of EPA Decision Making. J. Polit. Economy 100, 175-197. Dolinoy, D.C., Miranda, M.L., 2004. GIS Modeling of Air Toxics Releases from TRI-Reporting and Non-TRI-Reporting Facilities: Impacts for Environmental Justice. Environmental Health Perspectives 112, 1717-1724. E.P.A, 2004. National Monitoring Strategy: Air Toxics Component. U.S. Environmental Protection Agency, Office of Air Quality Planning and Standards. Accessed from on EPA, 1999a. The Benefits and Costs of the Clean Air Act, 1990 to 2010. EPA-410-R-99-001, Office of Air and Radiation, Washington, DC. Accessed from on 31 EPA, 1999b. Residual Risk Report to Congress. US Environmental Protection Agency, Office of Air and Radiation, Office of Air Quality Planning and Standards. Accessed from on EPA, 2000. National Air Toxics Program: The Integrated Urban Strategy’. Office of Air Quality Planning and Standards, Research Triangle Park, North Carolina, July, 99-007. EPA, 2001. Workplan for the National Air Toxics Program and Integrated Air Toxics State/local/tribal Program Structure. Emission Standards Division, Office of Air Quality Planning and Standards. Accessed from on EPA, 2003. International Analysis of Methane and Nitrous Oxide Abatement Opportunities: Report to Energy Modeling Forum. Accessed from http://www.epa.gov/climatechange/economics/pdfs/methodologych4.pdf on 18 February 2011 EPA, 2004a. National Monitoring Strategy: Air Toxics Component. U.S. Environmental Protection Agency, Office of Air Quality Planning and Standards. Accessed from on EPA, 2004b. Toolkit for Assessing Potential Allegation of Environmental Injustice. Office of Environmental Justice. Accessed from on EPA, 2006a. Air Toxics Risk Assessment Reference Library Volume 3, Community-Scale Assessment. Accessed from http://www.epa.gov/ttn/fera/risk_atra_vol3.html on EPA, 2006b. RAIMI – Regional Air Impact Modeling Initiative. Accessed from http://www.epa.gov/earth1r6/6pd/rcra_c/raimi/raimi.htm on 12 March 2006 EPA, 2007. SAB Advisory on EPA’s issues in valuing mortality risk reduction. Office of the Administrator, Science Advisory Board, October 12, 2007. Accessed from http://www.epa.gov/climatechange/economics/pdfs/methodologych4.pdf http://www.epa.gov/ttn/fera/risk_atra_vol3.html http://www.epa.gov/earth1r6/6pd/rcra_c/raimi/raimi.htm 32 http://yosemite.epa.gov/sab%5Csabproduct.nsf/4128007E7876B8F0852573760058A978/ $File/sab-08-001.pdf on 16 August 2010 EPA, 2008. Environmental Justice: Basic Information. Accessed from http://www.epa.gov/compliance/basics/ejbackground.html on 31 October, 2008 FR, 2005. Revision to the Guideline on Air Quality Models: Adoption of a Preferred General Purpose (Flat and Complex Terrain) Dispersion Model and Other Revisions, Final Rule. Federal Register, pp. 68217-68261. GAO, July, 2005. EPA Should Devote More Attention to Environmental Justice When Developing Clean Air Rules. GAO-05-289. Accessed from on Graham, J.D., 2007. The Evolving Regulatory Role of the U.S. Office of Management and Budget. Review of Environmental Economics and Policy 1, 171-191. Gupta, S., Van Houtven, G., Cropper, M., 1992. Paying for Permanence: An Economic Analysis of EPA's Cleanup Decisions at Superfund Sites. RAND J. Econ. 27, 563-582. Hammitt, J.K., 2000. Valuing mortality risk: theory and practice. Environmental Science & Technology 34, 1396-1400. Hanemann, M., 2008. California's New Greenhouse Gas Laws. Review of Environmental Economics and Policy 2, 114-129. Hartman, R.S., Wheeler, D., Singh, M., 1997. The cost of air pollution abatement. Appl. Econ. 29, 759-774. Heinzerling, L., Steinzor, R.I., 2004. A Perfect Storm: Mercury and the Bush Administration, Part II. Environmental Law Reporter 34, 10485-10497. http://yosemite.epa.gov/sab%5Csabproduct.nsf/4128007E7876B8F0852573760058A978/$File/sab-08-001.pdf http://yosemite.epa.gov/sab%5Csabproduct.nsf/4128007E7876B8F0852573760058A978/$File/sab-08-001.pdf http://www.epa.gov/compliance/basics/ejbackground.html 33 Karvosenoja, N., Johansson, M., 2003. Cost curve analysis for SO2 and NOx emission control in Finland. Environmental Science & Policy 6, 329-340. Kilmont, Z., Amann, M., Cofala, J., 2000. Estimating costs for controlling emissions of volatile organic compounds (VOC) from stationary sources. International Institute for Applied Systems Analysis, Austria. Accessed from http://www.iiasa.ac.at/Admin/PUB/Documents/IR-00-051.pdf on 18 February 2011 Krupnick, A., 2007. Mortality-risk valuation and age: stated preference evidence. Review of Environmental Economics and Policy 1, 261. Mariam, Y., Barre, M., 1996. VOCs’s cost functions in the design of emission abatement strategies. MPRA Paper No. 658. Accessed from on Minkler, M., Vasquez, V.B., Tajik, M., Petersen, D., 2008. Promoting Environmental Justice Through Community-Based Participatory Research: The Role of Community and Partnership Capacity. Health Education & Behavior 35, 119. Morello-Frosch, R., Pastor, M., Sadd, J., 2001. Environmental Justice and Southern California's" Riskscape": The Distribution of Air Toxics Exposures and Health Risks Among Diverse Communities. Urban Affairs Review 36, 551. Noonan, D.S., 2008. Evidence of Environmental Justice: A Critical Perspective on the Practice of EJ Research and Lessons for Policy Design. Social Science Quarterly 89, 1153-1174. NRC, 2004. Air quality management in the United States. National Academies Press, Washington, D.C. O’Neil, S.G., 2007. Superfund: Evaluating the Impact of Executive Order 12898. Environmental Health Perspectives 115, 1087. http://www.iiasa.ac.at/Admin/PUB/Documents/IR-00-051.pdf 34 Petersen, D., Minkler, M., Vasquez, V.B., Baden, A.C., 2006. Community-Based Participatory Research as a Tool for Policy Change: A Case Study of the Southern California Environmental Justice Collaborative. Review of Policy Research 23, 339-354. Post, E., McCubbin, D., Belova, A., Huang, J., Frey, N., 2009. Methodology for Distributional Benefit Analysis of a National Air Quality Rule. Report Prepared for EPA/NCEE by Abt Associates. Accessed from http://yosemite.epa.gov/ee/epa/eerm.nsf/vwAN/EE-0520- 01.pdf/$file/EE-0520-01.pdf on 10 February 2011 Ringquist, E.J., Clark, D.H., 1999. Local Risks, States' Rights, and Federal Mandates: Remedying Environmental Inequities in the US Federal System. Publius: The Journal of Federalism 29, 73. Ringquist, E.J., Clark, D.H., 2002. Issue definition and the politics of state environmental justice policy adoption. International Journal of Public Administration 25, 351-389. Rousseau, S., Proost, S., 2005. Comparing environmental policy instruments in the presence of imperfect compliance–A case study. Environ. Resource Econ. 32, 337-365. Sexton, K., 1997. Sociodemographic aspects of human susceptibility to toxic chemicals: Do class and race matter for realistic risk assessment? Environmental Toxicology and Pharmacology 4, 261-269. Su, J.G., Larson, T., Baribeau, A.M., Brauer, M., Rensing, M., Buzzelli, M., 2007. Spatial Modeling for Air Pollution Monitoring Network Design: Example of Residential Woodsmoke. Journal of the Air & Waste Management Association 57, 893-900. UWF, 2011. Partnership for Environmental Research and Community Health (PERCH). Accessed from http://uwf.edu/cedb/perch.cfm on 11 February 2011 http://yosemite.epa.gov/ee/epa/eerm.nsf/vwAN/EE-0520-01.pdf/$file/EE-0520-01.pdf http://yosemite.epa.gov/ee/epa/eerm.nsf/vwAN/EE-0520-01.pdf/$file/EE-0520-01.pdf http://uwf.edu/cedb/perch.cfm 35 Vajjhala, S., 2007. Building Community Capacity? Mapping the Scope and Impacts of the EPA Environmental Justice Small Grants Program. Resources for the Future. Accessed from on van Houtven, G., Cropper, M.L., 1996. When is a life too costly to save? The evidence from US environmental regulations. J. Environ. Econ. Manage. 30, 348-368. Williams, A., 2007. Louisville 2005: STAR Adopted. Accessed from http://www.louisvilleky.gov/APCD/STAR/ on 16 April 2007 Zhu, Y., Hinds, W.C., Kim, S., Sioutas, C., 2002. Concentration and Size Distribution of Ultrafine Particles Near a Major Highway. Journal of the Air & Waste Management Association 52, 1032-1042. http://www.louisvilleky.gov/APCD/STAR/ 36 Table 1 Details of Cost Function Parameters Used in Empirical Analysis Facility Source Pollutants Emitted Cost Parameters ija ijb IP Bleaching Line Vent Acetaldehyde 5303579 (1230) -0.019 (0.0001) Pulping System Vent Formaldehyde, Acetaldehyde, Benzene 27600000 (2.17e+06) -0.005 (0.0013) GP Boiler Formaldehyde, Acetaldehyde, Benzene 755887 (48729) -0.083 (0.013) Boiler Formaldehyde, Acetaldehyde, Benzene 755887 (48729) -0.083 (0.013) Boiler Formaldehyde, Acetaldehyde, Benzene 755887 (48729) -0.083 (0.013) Boiler Nickel, Arsenic 755887 (48729) -0.083 (0.013) SO Maelic Anhydride Plant Vent Formaldehyde, Acetaldehyde, Benzene 1214368 (551409) -0.066 (0.013) AP Methylamine Plant Vent Formaldehyde, Acetaldehyde, Benzene 1214368 (551409) -0.066 (0.013) SF Fugitive Emissions Acrylonitrile 25600000* -3.225* Fugitive Emissions Acrylonitrile 25600000* -3.225* Fugitive Emissions Acrylonitrile 25600000* -3.225* FG Turbine Formaldehyde, Acetaldehyde, Benzene 2248523* -6.307* SR Turbine Formaldehyde, Acetaldehyde, Benzene 2248523* -6.307* Turbine Formaldehyde, Acetaldehyde, Benzene 2248523* -6.307* TEG Reboiler Benzene 31863* -0.112* For cost parameters, numbers in parentheses indicate standard errors *Standard errors could not be estimated due to low sample size 37 Table 2 Emission Standards for Regulation at Various Spatial Resolutions (Threshold Risk = 1.0E-04; VSL=$5.5 Million) Facility Pollutant Baseline Emissions (T/Y) Optimal Emissions (TPY) Tract Block Group Block IP Acetaldehyde 5.5 149.6 149.6 196.4 Formaldehyde 8.5 0 0 0 Acetaldehyde 50.9 135.1 135.1 69.3 Benzene 5.08 0 0 0 SO Formaldehyde 0.0436 1.57 1.57 7.87 Acetaldehyde 0.00575 28.6 28.6 34.9 Benzene 0.00052 9.35 9.35 15.6 SF Acrylonitrile 2.819 0.11 0.11 0.03 Acrylonitrile 5.48 0.28 0.28 0.21 Acrylonitrile 1.159 0.17 0.17 0.07 AP Formaldehyde 0.869 0 0 0 Acetaldehyde 0.073 4.25 4.25 10.7 Benzene 0.03 0 0 0 SR Formaldehyde 30.52 1.02 1.02 1.07 Acetaldehyde 2.561 1.30 1.30 1.35 Benzene 1.0405 1.10 1.10 1.15 Formaldehyde 0.01027 1.06 1.06 1.11 Acetaldehyde 0.00135 1.34 1.34 1.39 Benzene 0.000123 1.14 1.14 1.19 Benzene 1.3 0 0 0 FG Formaldehyde 78.8 1.15 1.15 1.20 Acetaldehyde 6.615 1.43 1.43 1.48 Benzene 2.687 1.23 1.23 1.28 GP Formaldehyde 0.031 14.9 14.9 18.4 Acetaldehyde 0.000006 36.3 36.3 39.8 Benzene 0.00087 21.1 21.1 24.5 Formaldehyde 0.00098 24.2 24.2 27.0 Acetaldehyde 0.0000002 45.6 45.6 48.4 Benzene 0.000028 30.4 30.4 33.1 Formaldehyde 0.00228 37.8 37.8 40.2 Acetaldehyde 0.0000004 59.2 59.2 61.6 Benzene 0.0000621 44.0 44.0 46.4 Nickel 0.4095 0 0 0 Arsenic 0.438 0 0 0 38 Table 3 Emission Standards for Regulation at Various Spatial Resolutions (Threshold Risk = 1.0E-05; VSL=$5.5 Million) Facility Pollutant Baseline Emissions (TPY) Optimal Emissions (TPY) Census Tract Block Group Block IP Acetaldehyde 5.5 112.0 113.9 96.9 Formaldehyde 8.5 0 0 0 Acetaldehyde 50.9 0 0 0 Benzene 5.08 0 0 0 SO Formaldehyde 0.0436 0 0 0 Acetaldehyde 0.00575 17.5 17.0 16.4 Benzene 0.00052 0 0 0 SF Acrylonitrile 2.819 0 0 0 Acrylonitrile 5.48 0.06 0.06 0.03 Acrylonitrile 1.159 0 0 0 AP Formaldehyde 0.869 0 0 0 Acetaldehyde 0.073 0 0 0.54 Benzene 0.03 0 0 0 SR Formaldehyde 30.52 0.90 0.90 0.86 Acetaldehyde 2.561 1.2 1.19 1.14 Benzene 1.0405 0.99 0.99 0.94 Formaldehyde 0.01027 0.94 0.94 0.94 Acetaldehyde 0.00135 1.22 1.22 1.22 Benzene 0.000123 1.02 1.02 1.02 Benzene 1.3 0 0 0 FG Formaldehyde 78.8 1.03 1.03 1.06 Acetaldehyde 6.615 1.31 1.31 1.35 Benzene 2.687 1.11 1.11 1.14 GP Formaldehyde 0.031 6.10 5.48 3.22 Acetaldehyde 0.000006 27.5 26.9 24.6 Benzene 0.00087 12.3 11.6 9.4 Formaldehyde 0.00098 15.4 15.2 13.3 Acetaldehyde 0.0000002 36.8 36.6 34.7 Benzene 0.000028 21.6 21.4 19.5 Formaldehyde 0.00228 29.0 29.1 27.4 Acetaldehyde 0.0000004 50.4 50.5 48.8 Benzene 0.0000621 35.2 35.2 33.5 Nickel 0.4095 0 0 0 Arsenic 0.438 0 0 0 39 Table 4 Mean Individual Cancer Risk in EJ and non-EJ communities 100 in a Million Threshold 10 in a Million Threshold Resolution of Regulation Mean Individual Risk in “communities of concern” Mean Individual Risk for all other communities Mean Individual Risk in “communities of concern” Mean Individual Risk for all other communities Census Tract 12.4 (n=2446) 9.6** (n = 4701) 4.8 (n=2446) 3.6** (n = 4701) Census Block 14.1 (n=2446) 10.7** (n = 4701) 4.1 (n=2446) 3.1** (n = 4701) ** Difference in mean individual risk between communities of concern and other communities is significant at 1%; All cell values are “n in a million” units Figure 1 Spatial Distribution of Cancer Risks under Regulation at Census Tract Resolution (Cancer Risk Threshold of 100 in a Million) 41 Figure 2 Spatial Distribution of Cancer Risks under Regulation at Census Block Resolution (Cancer Risk Threshold of 100 in a Million) 42 Figure 3 Spatial Distribution of Cancer Risks under Regulation at Census Tract Resolution (Cancer Risk Threshold of 10 in a Million) 43 Figure 4 Spatial Distribution of Cancer Risks under Regulation at Census Block Resolution (Cancer Risk Threshold of 10 in a Million) Figure 5 Share of Expected Additional Annual Cancer Cases Relative to Share of Population at Tract and Block Resolution of Regulation for Whites and Nonwhites (Risk Threshold: 100 in a Million) E J P O P Nonwhites Whites 45 Figure 6 Share of Expected Additional Annual Cancer Cases Relative to Share of Population at Tract and Block Resolution of Regulation for Whites and Nonwhites (Risk Threshold: 10 in a Million) E JP O P Nonwhites Whites work_g26mpmcmbzcmjjkgjmvbayivqy ---- Genocide and Transitional Justice | Scholarly Publications Skip to main content Leiden University Scholarly Publications Home Submit About Select Collection All collections This collection Academic speeches Dissertations Faculty of Archaeology Faculty of Governance and Global Affairs Faculty of Humanities Faculty of Science Faculty of Social and Behavioural Sciences Leiden Journals, Conference Proceedings and Books Leiden Law School Leiden University Press Medicine / Leiden University Medical Centre (LUMC) Research output UL Search box Persistent URL of this record https://hdl.handle.net/1887/70120 Documents Download Genocide and Transitional Justice Not Applicable (or Unknown) open access Full text at publishers site In Collections This item can be found in the following collections: Institute for History Regilme, S.S. (2017) Genocide and Transitional Justice Article / Letter to editor All authors Regilme, S.S. Date 2017-02-10 Journal Human Rights Review Volume 18 Issue 1 Pages 111 - 116 DOI doi:10.1007/s12142-016-0448-9 Link http://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s12142-016-0448-9 ©2020-2021 Leiden University A service provided by Leiden University Libraries Contact About us Recently Added Digital Collections Student Repository work_g4ixiyvq6zhxfjpz2pq4i6c65i ---- JSS-29-2-183-11-1133-Obioha-U-P-Tt.pmd The Nature of Justice Uwaezuoke Precious Obioha Department of Philosophy, Faculty of Arts, Olabisi Onabanjo University, P.M.B. 2002, Ago-Iwoye, Ogun State, Nigeria Telephone: +234-803-3950-443, E-mail: unclepees@yahoo.com KEYWORDS Rights. Distributive. Equality. Fairness. Difference Principle. Commutative ABSTRACT Since the Renaissance period in history initiated the act of free thinking and independent thought, there have existed and still exist various notions and perspectives over every single subject of human discourse. The concept of justice is a good example. There are shades of opinion and views concerning the nature of justice. Consequent upon this, human relationships and co-existence have become precarious as a result of wrong or inadequate conceptions of justice. This is particularly true, I believe, because justice is a basic imperative for good human relationships and co-habitation. In this paper therefore, I have tried to analyze the various conceptions of justice and the implications of such conceptions to human quest for peaceful co-existence and the full realization of human potentials. At the end I argue that justice as fairness, better than every other conception of justice, provides answers to man’s quest for a global social order requisite for human flourishing any time and any day. INTRODUCTION The need and the quest for justice in the mi- cro and macro societies and by extension the global world is increasingly becoming inevitab- le in the wake of all kinds of violence and orch- estrated social disorder and break down of law that characterize our world today. Justice cuts across and assumes a high degree of importan- ce in every sphere of human endeavor such that it is a recurrent concept, an ideal in ethics, juris- prudence, governance and every other form of human undertaking that involve human rela- tionships, management and administration. At the intrapersonal and interpersonal levels, it is a cardinal virtue such that with it global peace is guaranteed and without it our world will re- main a place of horror and discomfort. As a re- sult of this, the concept of Justice has become real and very topical in contemporary societies. Verily, we do have an insight into the reality of justice whenever somebody cheats us or our group is marginalized in the share and distribu- tion of national resources and properties. How- ever, the concept of justice cuts across national boundaries and assumes a very important place in international politics, that is, politics between and among states. There is something anthropologically and ontologically common to man and objects, cre- atures and phenomena of the universe. This co- mmonness lies in the fact that all are parts that make up the universe whose origin is a mystery which man is one. The ‘life’ of one part may not be known by the other, yet each part obeys the rhythm of nature who has judiciously assigned the respective parts their respective purposes, agenda, mission and reasons for existence. The universe’s natural order is never an accident or a coincidence. It is not only teleological, but also a milieu of commitments and avoidances. Each object of nature (both animate and inanimate) desires to herself a breathing place in the natu- ral space, herself being natural too, to fulfill her innate or natural callings, to avoid threats from other objects of nature and exercise the freedom necessary for her existence. Against this background, the history of jus- tice is as old as the history of man. This follows, therefore, that justice is natural to man. Man has never bothered himself with what justice means since it is a natural law. Instead the problematic of natural justice has bordered on its hermeneu- tics. It borders on justice calculus – what natural justice is and what it is not (Dukor 2003). Although justice has taken the coloration of cultures, philosophies, individuals and sch- ools of thought, still the bottom line of this con- cept is that it is synchronically (a historical) in terms of definition. Whatever differences there may be in the definition of justice by scholars, broadly speaking, the concept pictures integrity, impartiality, rightness and fairness as constitut- ing the notion of justice. However, more funda- mental to the concept of natural justice are nat- ural rights, which constitute the most original, inalienable and natural, form of justice. In rec- ognition to this, the ‘United Nation’ Charter on © Kamla-Raj 2011 J Soc Sci, 29(2): 183-192 (2011) Fundamental Human Rights and Nigerian Con- stitution chapter IV, outline the fundamental hu- man rights as follows: Right to life, right to dignity of human person; right to personal liberty; right to fair hearing; right to private and family life; right to freedom of thought, conscience and religion; right to peaceful assembly and association, right to freedom of movement; right to freedom from discrimination; compulsory acquisition of property; restriction on and derogation from fundamental rights and special jurisdiction of High Court and Legal aid (Nigerian Consti- tution 1989). Be that as it may, it is pertinent that we co- nceptualize justice for proper understanding and application. This we shall do through the optic of various philosophers and jurists across epochs and periods. Hence, the concept and the meaning of justice. THE CONCEPT OF JUSTICE Ogunmodede (2005) identifies justice as the oldest human virtues in the world. It is mentio- ned among the 42 virtues of “Negative Confes- sions” called the Book of the Dead (Hilliard 1987) by the Ancient Black Egyptians. The Egyp- tian term “Maat” is the oldest word for justice and it means “truth, justice and righteousness” of life among men and before the gods. In view of the various meaning to the concept of justice, Macquarrie (1967) in the “Dictionary of Ethics” opines that several meanings can be actually given to justice, namely: Justice in the oldest se- nse; justice in the narrow sense; and justice in the proper sense. In the oldest sense, as contained in the An- cient Egyptian Wisdom Literature and Old Te- stament, justice means moral “righteousness, re- ctitude or moral excellence, or perfection”. In order to be in communion with the spirit of the gods and to be found worthy on judgment day, man must live a righteous and perfect life. The oldest existing work in the world, the teachings of Ptah Hotep in this sense can be aptly describ- ed as the oldest document on past living among men. In the narrow sense, justice means conform- ity with the law. However, the limitation of this sense of justice is two-fold. One, an unjust law is no law at all. Two, conforming to written or legal law without the spirit of justice shows the inadequacy and defects of justice in the narrow sense. While in the proper sense, justice is un- derstood as the “harmonious functioning of the constituent parts in the individual, or in the state. It is in this sense that Plato understands and de- fines justice. Plato accepts justice as the basis of society and goes on to emphasize another as- pect of it. “Justice is keeping what is properly one’s own and doing one’s own job”. Plato says: Justice is the requirement we laid down at the beginning as of universal application when we founded our state, or else some form of it. We lay down; if you remember and have often repeated that in our state, one man was to do one job, he was naturally most suited for (Plato 1974). It is obvious that Plato dislikes amateurish- ness and meddlesomeness because this duo ch- aracterized the Athenian city of his time which to him brought about its ruin and decay. Plato therefore added, ‘justice consists in minding yo- ur own business and not interfering with oth- er people. Before Plato, Ptah-Hotep in his 5th instructions or, teachings defines Maat (Justice) as the basis of good governance. He says: If you are a man who leads, a man who controls the affairs of many, then, seek the most perfect way of performing your responsibility so that your conduct will be blameless. Great is Maat (truth, justice, righteousness). It is everlasting. Maat has been unchanging since the time of Asar. To create obstacle to the following of laws is to open a way to a condition of violence. The transgressor of laws is puni- shed; although the greedy person overlooks this. Baseness may obtain riches; yet crime never lands its waves on the shore. In the end, only Maat lasts. Man says: Maat is my father’s ground (Hilliard 1987). In another place in the 19th instruction, he defines distributive justice as “rightness” or “straight line” which is an antidote for the vice of greed. Greed is a grievous sickness that has no cure. There is no treatment for it. It is com- pound of all evil…. That person endures whose rule is rightness, who walks a straight line, for that person will live a legacy by such behavi- our (Hilliard 1987). Aristotle regards justice as the sovereign vi- rtue and the major purpose of the state. Justice is treating equals equally and unequals unequal- ly and in proportion to their relevant differen- ces (Aristotle 1976). He further maintains that UWAEZUOKE PRECIOUS OBIOHA184 “unjust means either lawless or unfair; therefo- re justice means either lawful or just”. Howev- er, if positive law theory is anything to go by, then Aristotle’s definition of justice as confor- mity to law reduced the concept of justice to le- gality. The implication is that the concept of ju- stice could as well be replaced by legality. On the contrary, we argue that justice is also appea- led to in matters where there is no positive law. More so, it is justice that supplies the criteria of law as well as judges its justification. There- fore, justice cannot be synonymous with lega- lity since it transcends it and gives it its justifi- cation. In Plato’s Republic, Thrasymachus defines justice as “the interest of the stronger”. Thrasy- machus is portrayed as the sophist who asserted that injustice is to be preferred to the life of ju- stice. He sees nothing wrong with injustice. He goes ahead to consider the unjust to be positi- vely superior in character and intelligence. He says, “injustice pays” not at the meager level of the pick pocket, although there is profit in that too, but especially in the case of those who car- ry injustice to perfection and make themselves masters of cities and nations. According to him, “justice is pursued by simpletons and leads to weakness. He held that people should aggres- sively pursue their own interests in a virtually unlimited form of self-assertion, and thus sees justice as the interest of the stronger having be- lieved “might to be right”. Laws are made by the ruling party for its own interest and these laws define what is right meaning that what is right is the same everywhere. This reductionist concep- tion of justice goes without grave consequen- ces for human existence and global interaction. It reduces morality to brute and naked power. The effect of this in our global world is obvious and apparent. People rise against people; cities rise against cities; the powerful against the we- ak; the powerful nations always threaten the we- ak ones; dictate to them almost in all things in- cluding how they (the weak nation) should run their governments. They even (the stronger na- tions) go to the extent of choosing their rulers for them against their (the citizens of the weak nations) wish. The powerful nations do this with reckless abandon provided it serves their inter- ests-the interest of the mighty counts, that of the weak is a non issue. Imagine the implications of this in our global world. It is that of rancor, war and violation. It consequently degenerates to the state of nature of Thomas Hobbes where life is solitary, nasty, poor, brutish and short. The influence of this Thrasymachean view of justice was obvious on Thomas Hobbes who ev- en after coming out of the state of nature could not rise above “the interest of the stronger” in his civil society. His theory on what constitutes justice is contained in his major works as “De Cive” (on the citizens) 1642, “Human Nature” published together with “De Corpore political” (republication of De Cive in 1650) under the single title “Eternal Law”. For Hobbes, the in- teraction of naturally free human beings, the push and pull of efficient cause (fear of death) and final cause (desire for happiness, or a more contended life) combined to bring “state of na- ture” to the point at which the transformatory social contract was made not between the ruler and the ruled but among the people who wanted to transcend the state of nature. Hobbes’ con- tract theory confers power on one man or ass- embly of men, without which it can be enfor- ced. It is a contract made by the citizens with each other to obey such ruling power, as the majority shall choose. When they have chosen, the citizens lose all right except such as the gov- ernment may find it expedient to grant. “There is no right of rebellion, because the ruler is not bound by any contract, whereas the subjects are” (Russell 1979). According to Hobbes, the sovereign’s job is the procurement of safety for the people and by safety is meant not a bare preservation of li- fe but also all the other contentment of life wh- ich every man by lawful industry, without da- nger or hurt to the common wealth, shall acqu- ire to himself. His view of political authority makes the sovereignty of the ruler inviolable and thus his “Leviathan” could be a tyrant who may choose not to recognize individual freed- om and aspiration. Another philosopher or rather political the- orist who was greatly influenced by the Thrasy- machean view on justice was Niccolo Machia- velli (1469 – 1527). Though not explicitly wri- tten as a title, his thoughts on justice and the st- ate are contained in his two famous books, “The Prince” and “Discourses on the first Decade on Titus Livinus”. He started the ‘The Prince’ with a question asking how many kinds of principa- lities there are and the way in which they are acquired. What is principality? It is defined as sovereignty, territory of a prince or a prince hi- THE NATURE OF JUSTICE 185 mself. In his works, he advocates the principle where the ruler must be firm and unyielding wh- ile feigning to be virtuous. To him, it is more im- portant to retain political power than to seek to take over one. It is better for the prince to be feared than to be loved. The prince should not bother himself about morality and religion but because man is pretentiously moral and religi- ous, the prince could exploit this quality in man to his own advantage. Since morality and reli- gion make man susceptible to deceit, fickleness and feebleness, the prince can exploit this to en- hance his political gains. The Prince must be ab- ove the law and outside morality in order to co- nveniently and successfully carry out his task of unification, consolidation and influence. To be able to do this, the Prince must freely use as his tools perfidy, cruelty, murder and any other means acceptable to him. Machiavelli despises morality because for him the first law of politics is expediency and not moral consideration. He rejects meekness, patience and true justice but in their place he enthrones vitality, energy, str- ength of character, ability to achieve one’s aim, desire for fame, courage, patriotism, ability to win power and preserve it. The goal achievab- le by these means is what matters to him irre- spective of the morality or immorality of the means, thus his famous dictum: “the end justi- fies the means”. An outright opposite to the Thrasymachean view of justice is Thomas Aquinas conception of justice. Aquinas defines justice as “a perpet- ual and constant will of giving everyone his due”. In this view, the angelic doctor St Thomas Aq- uinas recognizes justice as a moral virtue rooted in the will which includes other’s welfare. This is essential because since the will necessarily seeks the good whether the good in itself or the proximate good of the individual, it would need a virtue that will make it possible for the respect of the other. Readen (1979) recognizes this con- ception of justice as one of the classical account of justice found in the institute of Justinian. The other classical account of justice is the one pr- eferred by Emmanuel Kant which was offered by a celebrated jurists Ulpian as “to live honor- ably, to injure nobody, to give every person his due”. In view of this, Kant states that every ac- tion is just in itself or in its maxim if “the free- dom of the will of each can co-exist together with the freedom of everyone according to the universal laws” (Readen 1979). Spinoza (1951) also understand justice from the Justinian view when he says, “justice is the ha- bitual rendering of everyman his lawful due, wh- ile injustice is depriving a man, under the pre- tence of legality, of what the law rightly inter- preted would allow him”. When Hegel conce- ives of justice, he conceives of man as having dignity and respect. Therefore, according to him, justice, in the sense of abstract right, is a kind of egalitarianism in which each person is respected because he is human, and exists in- dependent of the power of the state. Although he sees the justice of the state to be supreme and above the justice of the individuals, how- ever, he advocates for civil disobedience in ca- ses of unjust laws. His reason is that not all sta- tes and all laws should command obedience. According to him, a despotic government vitia- tes the law and does not deserve obedience. To support this claim, he insists that “insofar, as the state is the synthesis of particularity and uni- versality, of the family and the individual, there ought to be the preservation by the state of in- dividual liberty which the individual possesses as a member of civil society” (Stumph 1964). For Hume (1964) the concept of Distributi- ve Justice is contingent upon the economic co- nditions and needs of man. This is because of the scarcity of resources, goods and services in view of the multiplicity of human needs and wa- nts that have arisen. If such goods and services were in abundance, the concept of justice in th- eir distribution would never have occurred to anyone. He says, “What purpose makes a par- tition of goods where everyone has already mo- re than enough?” However, if the scarcity of ne- eded goods or services were so extreme that the- re is no way to prevent the majority of the po- pulation from perishing and the remainder from suffering extreme deprivation and misery, then the strict laws of justice are suspended in such a pressing emergency and give place to the str- onger motives of necessity and self-preservati- on. And whenever we can imagine such condi- tions to have always obtained, there the concept of Distributive Justice would not have risen, co- ncluded Ogunmodede (2005). From the foregoing, almost all the definitions of justice (in its proper sense) we have consid- ered point to the conclusion that justice is giving one his or her due. Although, the concept of ‘giv- ing one his or her due’ raises a fundamental pro- blem here, for instance, what determines rights UWAEZUOKE PRECIOUS OBIOHA186 and dues or what justifies claims? Is it not the individual alone that knows what is due to him or her? Even when we claim through “public interest” to know what is in the best interest of a person, often times we have misunderstood a person’s interest and thus misrepresent it. If in- dividuals are the true representatives of their in- dividual interest, how then do we know what is due to people? However, it seems that the concept of right or natural right or what is commonly called the fundamental human right has answers to this question. The place of right in the understand- ing of justice and its application cannot be over- emphasized such that the notion of justice and its applications become a mere play on words, without recognition of the concept of right. Ar- istotle is one of the outstanding proponents of natural right theory. This theory holds that na- tural right is the ultimate basis of justice. Man has right not primarily because he has received them by society, but because his nature as a hu- man being confers right upon him. The rights that are to be respected by justice primarily de- rive from the laws inherent in nature itself. Men and human communities have a natural right to well ordered existence, self-realization and pr- ogress. On a secondary level man’s rights also derive from the further determination of natur- al rights by the positive law of a community. The demands of natural right can usually be compli- ed with in different ways. For example property and inheritance rights and it is left to the comm- unity to determine in which concrete forms the- se demands shall be met with. However, posi- tive law must agree with demands of natural ri- ght as much as possible and may never contra- dict it, if it wants to be legitimate and binding. When Plato sees justice as the greatest of all virtues arising from the harmonization of the th- ree classes of the state and the three aspects of human soul, little did he know that he was lay- ing down a monumental principle that will gui- de the actions of individuals and states in gen- erations to come. Plato says: ‘justice in the state is the same as justice in the individual. It is the product of every one staying in his place and doing his task”. A proper understanding of Pla- to’s concept of justice shows that his concept of justice is more in line with the theory of justice as fairness. From the perspective of Rawls (1971), fair- ness ensures a just state. Thus, to him justice as fairness is a surer way of achieving a just social order. According to him, man is placed at the initial position of equality. They have knowle- dge of the general laws of psychology, but they are ignorant of particular facts both about them- selves and about the society in which they live. They are conceived to be self interested and ra- tional. In coming together to form a society they must agree on principles for the distribution of benefits and burdens. This agreement rests on the principle of equality both of basic rights and duties. Thus, Rawls sees justice as emanating fr- om the contractual hypothesis and it connotes nothing but fairness or more generally rightness. Curson corroborated this view when he defines justice as “the virtue which results in each per- son receiving his or her due. It is the quality of being right and fair (Adeigbo 1994). According to Rawls, to be fair in selecting the principles of justice, the possibility of bias must be removed. Fairness in his theory requi- res the more favored to agree to the type of dis- tributive rule they would prefer if they were not more favored. Rawls proposes that persons in an original position will or should agree that all social primary goods (for example, Basic liber- ties such as political freedom and freedom of choice in occupations, opportunity, income, we- alth and the bases of self-respect) are to be dis- tributed equally unless an unequal distribution of any or all of these goods is to the advantage of the least favored (Rawls 1971). For him ju- stice is an issue of fairness focusing on the dis- tribution of resources and permitting an uneq- ual distribution only to the extent that the weak- est members of society benefit from that inequ- ality. According to Rawls, even if an inequality does not harm the least well off, it is unjust if it leaves them no better off than before. This em- phasizes a distributionist type of justice and a defensible presumption in favor of equality in distribution of primary goods such as wealth and income. According to Younkins (2000), in Rawls’ di- fference principle, an inequality can be advan- tageous to the person who gets the smaller sh- are because inequalities can constitute incenti- ves which increase the size of the pie to be sha- red, so that the smaller piece may be larger in absolute terms than an equal share of the smal- ler pie that would have existed in the absence of such incentives. The difference principle col- lapses to strict equality under conditions where THE NATURE OF JUSTICE 187 differences in income and other rewards have no effect on the incentives of individuals. How- ever, in the real world currently and in the fore- seeable future, greater rewards bring forth grea- ter productive efforts, thus increasing the total wealth of the economy and under the difference principle, the wealth of the least advantaged. Edwards Younkins argues that Rawls does not see the natural endowments of individuals as their making and therefore, his difference pr- inciple is an agreement to consider the distribu- tion of natural talents as a common asset and to share in the fruits of this distributions, no matter what it ends up being in this view an individual’s natural endowments are not considered to be his own property, but rather the property of society. According to Gorr (1983), this is one of the fun- damental tenets of John Rawls’ theory of justice, “that we should seek a conception of justice that nullifies the accidents of natural endowment…as counters in quest for political and economic ad- vantage…” Now what makes Rawls’ idea of ju- stice so important is that he systematically ex- presses a vision that had already underpinned a great deal of social policy, legal theory and even international relations. The goal of Rawls’ con- ception of justice is to put certain segments of society in the position that they would have been in except for some underserved and unfortunate circumstances. Furthermore, Rawlsian idea that one’s own status, endowment, and wealth are unearned is especially potent when it is combined with (1) the Kantian notion that there is no vir- tue in pursuing one’s own personal flourishing and/or (2) the guilt felt by those who are asham- ed to live in material abundance while others in the world suffer. Kant advocates abject selfless- ness and held that an action is moral only if a person performs it out of a sense of duty without regard to any personal goal, desire, motive or in- terest (Kant 1959). If a person acts to derive ben- efit, his action is amoral. Furthermore, Kant wo- uld even maintain that no moral credit would accrue to a person who gains pleasure from his charitable activities even though he did not se- ek such pleasure. In addition, so-called politic- al guilt can be defined as the belief that one be- longs to a group of people that has unjustly or unduly fortunate circumstances, endowments, or privileges. However, Rawls’ theory of justice has come under heavy criticism. Rawls has been criticiz- ed for focusing on how goods are distributed among person ‘representative’ of various posi- tions in society but ignore which individuals ha- ve which goods and how they gained possess- ion of them. Critics of Rawls argue that people hold an entitlement to what they produce or ha- ve legitimately acquired and therefore should be protected from Rawls’ proposed redistribu- tionist policies (Younkins 2000). To them the Difference Principle is an unacceptable infrin- gement on liberty in that redistributive taxation to the poor requires the immoral takings of just holdings. Rawls’ opponents contend that the ju- stness or otherwise of income or wealth distri- bution depends only on the manner in which th- at distribution came about and not the pattern of the distribution itself. Another criticism levied against Rawls theory of justice is that fairness is not the proper stan- dard of justice because the world is inherently unfair and thus unjust. There is no equality in nature; some are smarter, more talented, better looking than others. People have the freewill to either use or not use the talents nature has en- dowed them with. Therefore economic equality is a goal incompatible with nature. True justice is attained when people’s lives and property are secure and they are free to own property, order its direction, determine the purpose to which their bodies are put, engage in consensual transact- ions and relationship with others and freely pu- rsue their conception of happiness. Further, his critics argue that Rawls fail to recognize that tal- ents are not a common pool, that the aptitudes that one person enjoys in no way lessens the num- ber and magnitude of abilities that are available to another. My talent is not acquired at anybo- dy’s expense. Thus, Rawls is rebelling against reality, nature and the existence of human talent. The existence of one’s talents is neither just nor unjust – it just is. So why should those “favored by nature” be made to pay for what is not a mo- ral problem or an injustice and is not of his or her own making, his critics argue. But for the fact that whatever one acquires is not of his own making, is the more reason such acquisition should be freely distributed. For the fact that our world is already lopsided and imbalanced as a result of nature’s inequality, then there is a mo- ral burden on those so blessed to freely give to those who are not so favored. So to that extent Rawls’ argument is tenable. Even Nozick’s (1983) entitlement theory and end state based on the principle that all human beings have UWAEZUOKE PRECIOUS OBIOHA188 absolute rights to their person and to the fruits of their labor could not provide the needed de- vastation of Rawlsian justice which Nozick in- tended. Justice has been classified into commutati- ve, distributive, contributive or legal, vindictive and social justice. Commutative justice demands that the exchange of goods and services should take place according to strict equality of values. This form of justice is also called contractual ju- stice because it is based on contract. And this is why it operates mainly in commercial exchange and just regulation of prices and wages. It leaves to everyone what is his or her own by right and attributes to him or her, what he or she really is. Distributive justice regulates the relations of a community with its members. It stipulates th- at advantages and burdens be distributed in the community according to proportionate equali- ty. Since individuals and groups are not equal in their qualification, resources and dedication to the common good, aids, burdens, honors must be distributed in proportion to needs, capabili- ties and merit, that is, according to proportion- ate equality. Contributive or legal justice is concerned with the general good of the community. It requires the members of a community to comply with the just demands of law for example; social legis- lation, taxation, National Youth Service Corps (NYSC). Legal justice obliges authorities to con- tribute to the common good by appropriate la- ws. Since the common good takes precedence over private interest, legal justice demands that the common good should not be sacrificed for the private interest of the individual or for his or her convenience. Another form of justice is vindictive (or Re- tributive) justice. This is a meeting out of a pro- portionate punishment to an offender for the of- fence committed, with a view to correct such an offender. This is in response to the natural ten- dency in human beings that evil must be pun- ished and good rewarded. However, the offender should not be punished beyond what he or she deserves and he or she should not be punished as a means of vengeance. Social justice on the other hand deals with the economic well-being of social groups. It de- als with the distribution of benefits and burd- ens throughout society. On the individual level, it demands a proportionate share of the benefits of economic endeavor of social partners, that is, proportionate distribution of the fruits of their labor so that no one is cheated in any manner. On the national level, every group demands a proportionate and equitable share of the nation’s wealth among various groups. It also demands that minority groups be not neglected. On the international level, social justice demands that the relationship between nations be guided by mutual respect of every nation. It imposes an obligation on developed nations of the world so that every nation will enjoy fruits of earth, and so, fully live as human beings. However, our interest lies more on distrib- utive and social justice for these forms of just- ice better exemplify what the relationship of in- dividuals to the state, and the state to the indi- viduals should be. It also establishes what the relationship between nations should be. THE PRINCIPLES OF JUSTICE As we have principles of physics within wh- ich the laws of nature guide all natural happen- ing in the world and in so doing prevent chaos in the order of nature, in no less, do we have prin- ciples guiding human conduct and the relation- ship existing between individuals on one hand and between individuals and the state on the other hand. In the same vein, there exist principles guiding the structuralization of the society. The later principle, we call principle of justice. Den Uyl and Rasmnssen (1998) distinguish between meta normative justice and justice as a constituent virtue of one’s personal flourishing. While meta normative justice is concerned with the orderly and peaceful coordination of any pe- rson with any other, justice as a normative pri- nciples and constituent virtue of a person’s con- textual recognition and evaluation of others ba- sed on objective criteria. Normative justice is concerned with selective relationships and re- quires practical reason and discernment of dif- ferences of both persons and situation. Justice as a constituent virtue deals with individuals in more specific and personal ways than does jus- tice in a meta normative sense. The question of how persons ought to act (normative justice) and the question of how society ought to be struc- tured (meta normative justice) are separate and distinct investigation. Nature has its own imperatives. As the wo- rld is governed by principles or laws that dictate how society ought to be structured in much the THE NATURE OF JUSTICE 189 same way do natural laws dictate how bridges or buildings should be constructed. Given the nature of man and the world, we should adopt and respect a social structure that accords each person a moral space over which he has freedom to act and within which no one else may right- fully interfere. Such structure would enable per- sons to pursue happiness, peace and prosperi- ty while living with one another. Younkins has argued that “the idea of natural rights can be used to create a legal system that makes it possible for individuals to pursue happiness and carry on a virtuous life”. From the foregoing, it suffices to argue that the fundamental principle of justice is respect for free and non-aggressive choice. Both justice and morality require respect for individual free choice. A state that restricts freedom of choice violates the basic principle of justice. Justice me- ans that a person must be accountable for his own actions, entitled to the reward of his labor and responsible for the consequences of his wrong-doing. Any violation of man’s right and freedom is an act of injustice against such man (although we are aware that man’s right and free- dom are not absolute and therefore can be lim- ited). Injustice therefore involves the violation of natural rights and includes murder, assault, theft, kidnapping, enslavement, rape, fraud, un- due interference, threat and intimidation etc. As this claim holds between states and individua- ls, so also it holds between nations at the inter- national level. On the normative justice, the relationship be- tween individuals and situation should reflect Kant’s imperative that persons should be treated as an end in themselves and never as a means. It is therefore a fundamental principle and require- ment of justice that persons apart from having natural rights also have dignity, respect and self worth and should be thus treated. Any act that disrespects their dignity, respect, self-worth and humanity is injustice against them. JUSTICE AND SOCIAL ORDER Social order refers to the social system as we- ll as a scheme of relations that defines the poli- tical, economic and social roles, rights and du- ties of a people in a society (Messner 1949:149). It is a state of harmonious relationship among individuals and groups that live in a society. So- cial order involves achieving co-operation for the common good of the members of a society through balancing of conflicts of interest amo- ng individuals and between individuals and the state, to this end, Kordig (1981) stresses that so- cial order is the end result of human arrangem- ents, values, norms, regulations, ideologies and institutions that enhance the proper function- ing of the various parts of society or community. In the light of the above importance of social order to human sociality, Aluko (2000) argues that the phenomenon of social order is an indis- pensable one to human existence. It is then safe to say that the attainment of peace, self and gro- up actualization as well as the general well-be- ing of all in a social system is a function of so- cial order. But what are the minimum requirements for the attainment and sustenance of social order? We consider these imperatives to be namely: co- mmon good, personality, solidarity, respect and subsidiarity. Common good affirms society’s du- ty to ensure common justice and fairness in the relationships between individuals. Personality affirms man’s dignity expressed through real pe- rsonal freedom, self actualization and respon- sibility and the accordance of necessary rights definitive of the person. Solidarity affirms co- operative togetherness and communion of all human persons. It demands a sharing of our var- ious qualities, characteristics and talented pro- ductivities. Such allows for man’s contribution to the common good. Respect involves revere- ncing the being, life and activities of other per- sons so long as such activities are not anti-so- cial. Subsidiarity holds that in the relationship between the individual and society, the subor- dinate group should have priority over the su- perior groups. One common factor however pervades these imperatives of social order. That factor is rela- tionships amongst individuals and between in- dividuals and society. But justice as fairness is necessary for cultivation and enduring of rela- tionships. Without justice rancor, distrust and cynicism enter relationships and everything falls apart. Therefore justice to me is the basic foun- dation for social order. Every other thing neces- sary for social order can be built on it. Except for the Thrasymachean “might is ri- ght” and Machiavellian “the end justifies the means”, Justice as fairness in giving people their due or justice as fairness in treating human be- ings in their humanity; in respecting their dig- UWAEZUOKE PRECIOUS OBIOHA190 nity, right and freedom. Justice as fairness in doing what one is naturally assigned to do; st- aying in one’s duty post without undue interfer- ence and meddlesomeness. Justice as fairness in bridging the gap and the gulf between the too- powerful nations and the weak nations; justice as fairness in closing the intimidating gap be- tween the wealthy, the very wealthy nations of the world and the poor and very poor nations, is the answer for social order. When people are denied their due, the natural thing is to seek re- dress. When the redress is not achieved through dialogue and other peaceful means, they resort to violence which characterizes social disorder. The activities of the Movement for the Emanci- pation of Niger Delta of Nigeria seem a good case in point. When the most powerful nations threaten and intimidate the weak ones for no just cause just to showcase their naked powers and tech- nology, just to show the weak nations that they (the too-powerful nations) are more powerful than them and therefore should be “feared and worshiped”, the result is for the weak to device means to free themselves over time, after all no- body is a monopoly of strength and violence. Hobbes (1980) puts it more succinctly in the st- ate of nature when he said: Nature hath made men so equal, in the faculties of the body, and mind; as that though there be found one man sometimes manifestly stronger in body, or quicker mind than another; yet when all is reckoned together, the difference between man, and man, is not so considerable, as that one man can there upon claim to himself any benefit to which another may not pretend as well as he for as to the strength of body, the weakest has strength enough to kill the strongest, either by secret machination, or by confederacy with other, that are in the same danger with himself. More so, when people experience undue in- terference in their territorial domain or even in their sovereignty as a state; and undue interfer- ence in their state policies and chosen way of governance by another state or power, experi- ence has shown that more often than not such activities have generated conflicts of interest which if not properly managed can and have led to various forms of social disorder. However, we do not claim to have exhaust- ed all there is in the nature of justice for the pe- aceful coexistence of humanity and the furth- erance of human happiness. Be that as it may, the proper sense of justice as presented here can be debated, refined and reconceptualized for the correction of human and social ills in the global order. CONCLUSION In this paper, we focused mainly on the na- ture of justice, concept of justice and the prin- ciples of justice. We saw that there is a rhythm in nature which both human and non- human ob- jects follow. We also saw that following from this rhythm, justice is natural to man and there- fore to deprive man justice is to deprive him of his humanity. Although there are differences in the definition of justice by scholars, however, broadly speaking, we pictured impartiality, in- tegrity, rightness and fairness as constituting the right notion of justice. We also identified as more fundamental to the concept of natural justice, na- tural rights which constitutes the most original, inalienable and natural form of justice. On this note we concluded the paper by advocating th- at respect to these imperatives should guide the relationships between individuals and nations whether in terms of socio-political relationships and or economic ties. This constitutes justice and will help correct human and social ills in the global order. REFERENCES Adeigbo FA 1994. Readings in Social and Political Philosophy. Vol 2. Ibadan: Claverianum Press. Aluko BA 2000. Philosophy, culture and the quest for social order in Africa. In: Kolawole Owolabi (Ed.): Issues and Problems in Philosophy. Ibadan: GROVACS Network, pp. 44-68 Aquinas Thomas 1981. Summa Theologiae. Maryland: Christian Classics. Aristotle 1976 Ethics. Trans. by JAK Thomson. England: Penguin Books Ltd. Bhandari DR Plato’s Concept of Justice, An Analysis. From (Retrieved February 12, 2010). Coplestone Frederick 1964. A History of Philosophy. Volume V, Part II. New York: Image Books. Dukor Maduabuchi 2003. Justice and the principle of necessity. In: Maduabuchi Dukor (Ed.): Philosophy and Politics: Discourse on Values, Politics and Power in Africa. Lagos: Malthouse Press, pp. 41-52. Gorr Michael 1983. Rawls on natural inequality. The Philosophical Quarterly, 33: 1-26 Hilliard Asa 1987. The Teachings of Ptah Hotep. Egypt: Blackwood Press. Hobbes Thomas 1980. The Study of Human Nature. New York: Oxford University Press. Kant Immanuel 1959. Foundations of the Metaphysics of THE NATURE OF JUSTICE 191 Morals. Translated by Lewis White Beck. Indianapolis: Bobbs Merrill. Kordig R 1981. A Theory of Rights. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 62: 171-192. Macquarrie John 1967. Justice. In: John Macquarrie (Ed.): A Dictionary of Ethics. London: S.C.M Press, pp.183- 188. Nozick Robert 1983. Distributive Justice. In: Michael Bayles, Kenneth Henley (Eds.): Right Conduct: Theories and Applications. New York: Random House, pp. 49-57. Ogunmodede Francis 2005. What is justice. In: Pantaleon Iroegbu (Ed.): Kpim of Morality, Ethics: General, Special and Professional. Ibadan: Heinemann Educational Books, pp. 401-415. Plato 1974 The Republic. Translated by Desmond Lee. England: Penguin Books Ltd. Rearden Myles 1987. Law and Justice. In: Myles Reardden (Ed.): Society and the Rule of Law. Lagos: Heinemann Press, pp. 112-114. Russell Bertrand 1979. The History of Western Philosophy. London: George Allen and Unwin. Spinoza B. 1951. A Theologico-political Treatise. New York: Penguin Books. Stumph Enoch 1964. Philosophy: History and Problems. New York: McGraw-Hill Inc. Rawls John 1971. A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, Massachusetts: The Belknap Press of Harvard University. Uyl D, Rasmnssen N 1998. Understanding Justice. New York: Random House. Younkins Edward 2000. Justice in a Free Society. From < h t t p : / / q u e b e c o i s l i b r e . o r g / y o u n k i n s 2 7 . h t m > (Retrieved June 20, 2009). UWAEZUOKE PRECIOUS OBIOHA192 work_gaowmrsjuranzeito25krp3uwq ---- 11-Bradford.PDF Rawlsian Justice and Preferences Over Work by Wylie Bradford wbradfor@efs.mq.edu.au Abstract Rawls’s assertion that the specification of property rights over the means of production is not determined by the theory of justice is shown to rest on shaky foundations. His account of the subjective circumstances of justice, which serve as an empirical constraint on the deliberations of those in the original position, is shown to reflect neoclassical economic theory in which preferences over work are excluded from welfare analysis. As a result, those in the original position are concerned only with the distributive outcomes of the basic structure, and not at all with its form in terms of the modalities of ownership of productive assets. This in turn is shown to conflict with Rawls’s professed methodology, in which constraints are not to be placed upon the conceptions of the good held by those in the original position. There is, however, very little scope for Rawls to amend his argument on this point without compromising the integrity of the whole. Hence, there is no good reason to exclude property rights over the means of production from consideration in the liberal theory of justice. JEL Classification: A13, D63, P16 1 Introduction* An important aspect of any discussion of economic justice is the question of property rights over the means of production. The significance of the issue follows from the obvious importance of such relations for the material productivity of any given society, and for the social relations that will emerge from the economic interactions of its citizens. Given the undeniable complexity of the issues involved, it is surprising that Rawls provides a disarmingly simple answer, one that survives through the considerable transformation that takes place in his overall theory of justice. For Rawls, the theory of justice provides no guidance on the question of whether private ownership of the means of production should be one of the institutions included in the basic structure of the just society (1971, henceforth TJ, p280).1 Instead, the principles of justice are to be derived separately, treating only as basic the right to personal property, leaving the specification of property rights over the means of production to be determined by the history and traditions of the society in question. This feature of Rawls's argument, whereby history is summarily accorded priority in terms of shaping the form of the basic structure, and is apparently immune to analysis in terms of the principles of justice, is referred to as historical dominance by Bradford (2000a). An obvious implication of historical dominance is that the parties in the original position are not concerned with the form of the basic structure (at least in terms of its ‘economic’ aspect), but rather only with its distributive outcomes. That is to say, they are not concerned whether a form of either capitalism or socialism obtains. This reflects the fact that, contra rights to personal property, property rights over the means of production are not considered basic. Hence, they need not receive the constitutional protection implied by the first principle of justice as fairness. In what follows, it is shown that Rawls’s argument rests, in part, on his reliance on neoclassical economic theory, as represented by Koopmans (1957). In particular, it is the assumptions concerning preferences over work (i.e. relating to different production processes) underlying that approach that leads Rawls to affirm the conditional comparability of outcomes, the claim that any specific desired welfare outcome is achievable under any assignment of property rights over the means of production. As the parties in the original position concern themselves only with the outcomes of the basic structure, it follows that the conditional comparability of outcomes suffices to render them uninterested in the specification of property rights over productive assets. However, it is demonstrated that the irrelevance of the form of the basic structure in Rawls’s argument is intimately related to his account of the circumstances of justice, particularly the subjective circumstances. The circumstances of justice are general facts, known to those behind the veil of ignorance, the function of which is to ensure that the conjectures of those in the original position remained tied to fundamental aspects of the reality to which they are to be applied. Rawls’s account of the subjective circumstances of justice is shown to be, in effect, a restatement of the neoclassical position regarding preferences over work; the circumstances of justice, in other words, are theoretical inferences rather than facts. Thus, the exclusive focus on the outcomes of the basic structure stems from assumptions made concerning the values of the parties to the deliberations in the * The author acknowledges the benefit of comments from Geoff Harcourt, Ken Tsutsumibayashi, Ugo Pagano and Rod O’Donnell. All are resolved of responsibility for any remaining errors. 1 This is despite the fact that he acknowledges that the arrangement of the background institutions of property is one of the “moral problems of political economy “ (TJ p265) 2 original position. This is inconsistent with Rawls’s insistence that no strong assumptions are made concerning the conceptions of the good held by the agents in the original position. Hence, Rawls can avoid consideration of property rights over the means of production only by ignoring his own methodological precepts. Furthermore, it is shown that the difficulties caused by Rawls’s account of the subjective circumstances of justice cannot be avoided without significant modifications of his central argument. The Circumstances of Justice In Section 40 of TJ, Rawls suggests an interpretation of the original position that is intended to imbue the device with more philosophical weight than it would have as a simple thought experiment.2 To this end he invokes Kant on the appropriate conception and bases of moral philosophy, and relates that his own approach is an attempt to conform to, and apply, Kantian principles. Kant, according to Rawls, holds that moral philosophy is the study of the “conception and outcome” of a “suitably defined rational decision” (TJ p251). Moral principles are “legislation for a kingdom of ends” and furthermore must be “agreed to under conditions that characterize men as free and equal rational beings” (TJ p252). When persons choose principles of action that express their nature as free and equal rational beings they are acting autonomously. This is to be contrasted with heteronomous action, which stems from principles chosen on the basis of social position, natural endowments, the type of society in which the person lives or the specific things which he/she desires. Rawls contends that the deliberative stage of the original position is a mechanism for realising Kant's conception of moral philosophy; the veil of ignorance prevents the parties from choosing heteronomous principles. As a result, the principles agreed to reflect the nature of persons as free and equal rational beings, and thus permit autonomous action. Furthermore, the principles of justice derived in the deliberative stage of the original position are categorical imperatives in Kant's sense. These are rules of conduct which apply to a person “in virtue of his nature as a free and equal rational being” (TJ p253). These are to be contrasted with hypothetical imperatives, which “[direct] us to take certain steps as effective means to achieve a specific end”, where the desire for the end involved is not a necessary condition for being a rational human being (ibid). Rawls asserts that the structure of the original position ensures that the principles of justice are categorical imperatives, as the argument for the principles is not based on the assumption that the parties have any particular ends. Instead they desire only the primary goods. This desire, based on the ‘thin theory of the good’, is part of the definition of rationality; as primary goods are all-purpose means to any end whatever, it is rational to want them regardless of other desires.3 Thus, 2 Strictly speaking, Rawls’s focus in this case is on the first stage of the four-stage sequence that makes up the original position. This first stage is denoted the deliberative stage by Bradford (2000a). The purpose of the deliberative stage is the derivation of the principles of justice – it is here that the ‘veil of ignorance’ is at its thickest. Rawls labels the subsequent stages of the original position the constitutional , legislative and judicial stages. He confuses the reader somewhat by continuing to use the term ‘original position’ to denote what is here called the deliberative stage, even after he has introduced the four-stage sequence as an elaboration of the original position device. 3 The ‘thin theory of the good’ is ‘thin’ in the sense that no assumptions are made concerning what individuals actually value, or ought to value. That is, they know that they possess a conception of the good without knowing to what it refers. The thin theory of the good is examined in more detail 3 to act from the principles of justice is to act from categorical imperatives in the sense that they apply to us whatever in particular our aims are. This simply reflects the fact that no such contingencies appear as premises in their derivation (TJ p253). Finally, Rawls contends that the deliberative stage can be interpreted as the viewpoint from which the noumenal self sees the world.4 It is at this point that he introduces a significant modification of the Kantian project. An obvious problem with viewing the parties in the original position as the collection of noumenal selves is that the latter are transcendental, lacking in empirical foundation. Sandel (1982 p13) notes that it is unclear how…abstract, disembodied [subjects] could without arbitrariness produce determinate principles of justice, or how in any case the legislation of such…[subjects] would apply to actual human beings in the phenomenal world. Rawls's response is to 'constrain' the hypothetical choice situation, from which the principles of justice are derived, in such a way as to ensure a determinate outcome applicable to actual human societies.5 He achieves this by allowing a minimal amount of empirical information to be available in the deliberative stage, namely, that the parties are aware that they are subject to the circumstances of justice (TJ pp. 126-128). The circumstances of justice comprise both the subjective and the objective. The aspect of the former stressed by Rawls in TJ is that the members of society are mutually disinterested; each has his or her own conception of the good, which they consider worthy of recognition and deserving of satisfaction, but they take no interest in the interests of others.6 Thus there are competing claims made on the benefits of social subsequently. 4 The noumenal self in Kant is the self qua subject of experience, the transcendental self, given prior to its ends. As Sandel (1982 p8) has it This something further [beyond the stream of sense data], which we cannot know empirically but must nonetheless presuppose as the condition of knowing anything at all, is the subject itself. The subject is the something 'back there', antecedent to any particular experience, that unifies our diverse perceptions and holds them together in a single consciousness. It provides the principle of unity without which our self-perceptions would be nothing more than a stream of disconnected and everchanging representations, the perceptions of no one. And while we cannot grasp this principle empirically, we must presume its validity if we are to make sense of self-knowledge at all. The converse of the noumenal self is the phenomenal self: the self qua object of experience, which can be empirically known and is subject to all the laws of nature and regularities of cause and effect. 5 Rawls claims that The theory of justice…tries to present a natural procedural rendering of Kant's conception of the kingdom of ends, and of the notions of autonomy and the categorical imperative. In this way the underlying structure of Kant's doctrine is detached from its metaphysical surroundings so that it can be seen more clearly and presented relatively free from objection (TJ p264). 6 As Rawls is committed to making no restrictive assumptions about the parties' conceptions of the good, he insists that the interests of individuals need not be egoistic, but could involve “ties of sentiment and affection” which would become known once the veil of ignorance is lifted (TJ p129). It is interesting to note Rawls's strange definition of egoism, and how it relates to the concept of primary 4 cooperation. Rawls argues that if this were not the case, if society was “an association of saints agreeing on a common ideal”, then justice would be nugatory (TJ p129). It is the fact that there is conflict over the distribution of primary goods which makes justice necessary, and establishes its primacy as a virtue.7 In his later work, Rawls (1993, henceforth PL) moves away from Kantian constructivism in favour of what he calls political constructivism. The essence of the change in perspective is that the principles of justice are no longer taken to represent a comprehensive moral doctrine shared by all citizens of the well-ordered society. Rather, they are a set of principles that are modular in character, capable of being affirmed by citizens holding a wide range of comprehensive doctrines without being seen to derive their legitimacy uniquely from any particular member of that set. As such, the case for the principles cannot be based, as in TJ, on the fundamental nature of human beings, an approach Rawls considers appropriate for a moral theory. Instead, the foundations of justice as fairness must be political in nature, reflecting the reality that modern democratic states are characterised by a plurality of comprehensive doctrines. Thus, in PL, Rawls defines the subjective circumstances of justice (SCJ) as the existence of pluralism as such, delimited to reasonable pluralism in the case of a well- ordered society of justice as fairness (p66). It is the awareness of the need to produce principles of justice that are compatible with this plurality of extant basic positions that represents the empirical constraint on the deliberations of the parties in the original position. Although this account is superficially different from that provided in TJ, it is apparent that beneath the fact of pluralism lies the reality of competing claims on resources and output. For instance, those moral (or religious) doctrines that hold that other sentient creatures ought not be utilised as food for humans imply very different usage patterns for land and other natural resources to those in which meat-eating is not proscribed. Conflicting moral positions on abortion or euthanasia can likewise be represented in terms of their differing claims regarding the allocation of health and medical resources, and the form of the output resulting from such allocations. On a grander scale, religious doctrines that differ on their attitudes to the moral worth of material gain, and ethical systems that weigh competitive and cooperative behaviour differently, will involve starkly contrasting distributive claims. Indeed, a society in which pluralism did not involve competing claims over resources and output would be goods. The primary goods are all-purpose means to any ends that may figure in a conception of the good. As such, it is implied that they cannot be desired for their own sake. As wealth and income, and powers and opportunities, figure among the primary goods it follows that these will not be ends pursued by any person. Now even casual observation of most human societies seems to make nonsense of this claim. The reasoning underlying this aspect of Rawls's argument is his definition of egoism. A conception of the good is considered to be egoistic if it treats “wealth, position, and influence, and the accolades of social prestige” (ibid.) as ends. By assuming that parties in the original position are not egoistic , Rawls at one definitional stroke ensures both that no person in the just society will desire wealth, prestige and power for their own sake, and, more importantly, that the device of primary goods is meaningful. Despite Rawls's claim that he makes no restrictive assumptions about the parties' conceptions of the good, it appears that without the restrictions entailed in the definition of egoism the parties in the original position would have nothing to distribute. In other words, the argument would stall at the outset. 7 Sandel (1982) replies ingeniously to this that, given this reasoning, the removal of the circumstances which give rise to the need for justice must be a virtue of equivalent importance to justice itself (pp. 31- 2). If the existence of danger makes physical courage a prized virtue, then the eradication of danger ought to be accorded the same importance as the inculcation of bravery. Rawls does not follow this route, and treats justice as strictly a remedial virtue. In this light, those who consider Rawls an apologist for mature American welfare capitalism are provided with telling ammunition. 5 perilously close to the “association of saints” in which discussions of justice have little import. Hence, other differences notwithstanding, the accounts of the SCJ in TJ and PL can be seen to share the feature that the presence of competing claims over the fruits of social cooperation represents a constraint to which the principles of justice formulated in the original position must conform. However, the fact of competing claims is not sufficient to establish the primacy of justice as a virtue, and so Rawls marries it with the objective circumstances of justice (OCJ). The most important of these is the moderate scarcity condition. The parties in the original position know that resources are not limitless, and that “mutually advantageous arrangements”, while feasible, will not be so productive as to satisfy all demands (TJ p127). The parties in the deliberative stage are aware that, beyond the veil of ignorance, the circumstances of justice hold. The only empirical information available to them, about the society in which they will live, is what they can infer from their knowledge that the circumstances of justice apply. Hence, although the parties in the deliberative stage have complete freedom to choose whatever principles of justice they desire, they also have a desire to express their nature as rational and equal members of the intelligible realm with precisely this liberty to choose, that is, as beings who can look at the world in this way and express this perspective in their life as members of society. They must decide, then, which principles when consciously followed and acted upon in everyday life will best manifest this freedom in their community, most fully reveal their independence from natural contingencies and social accident (TJ p255). Rawls contends that justice as fairness, a “theory of human justice” which “counts among its premises…the elementary facts about persons and their place in nature”, is the conception of justice that would satisfy these conditions in the deliberative stage (TJ p257). What is the connection between Rawls's use of the circumstances of justice as the empirical lifeline to the agents in the deliberative stage, and the central theme of this paper, the contention that in Rawls's system the form of the basic structure (particularly with respect to property rights in the means of production) is subordinate in importance to the distributive outcomes thereof? The answer lies in Rawls's understanding of the circumstances of justice. To him they are facts, the most elementary and general facts about persons and social reality. However, it is clear upon reflection that the circumstances of justice are not facts at all, but are better thought of as assumptions, or even theories, bristling with important, but perhaps hidden, implications. It is these implications which effectively force the parties in the original position to disregard the form of the basic structure, leaving it to be defined in accordance with historical dominance. That the circumstances of justice are assumptions is not a problem in itself; every argument requires premises. It is Rawls's conception of the nature of his enterprise that creates the difficulties to be spelt out below. He intends that the argument for justice as fairness should be “strictly deductive” and cites theories in politics and economics(!) as evidence of the fact that fully deductive theoretical schemes can be based on assumptions about human beliefs and interests. His ultimate aim is to achieve “a kind of moral geometry” with “all the rigor which this name connotes” (TJ p121). The problem of course is that the premises of Rawls's argument are poor analogues for the axioms of geometry. The latter are simple inventions which carry little, 6 if any, implicational baggage, and the primitives involved (such as 'point' and 'line') need not necessarily map onto features of observable reality as closely as the parties in the original position are meant to be connected to actual persons.8 By contrast, it will be argued that the circumstances of justice smuggle tacit premises into the deductive scheme, premises that skew the argument towards the position where the question of whether the just society is to be capitalist, socialist, or any other kind, is of little interest or import. The SCJ imply an unacknowledged restriction on the ends of the parties in the original position, in defiance of Rawls's self-imposed methodological precepts. And the OCJ unjustifiably render the question of property rights in the means of production superfluous in the deliberative stage via undefended assumptions about the nature of technology and its relationship to the institutions of production. 9 This contention, with regard to the SCJ, will now be elucidated.10 Outcomes, Forms and Preferences It is significant that Rawls stresses the 'competing claims' aspect of the SCJ.11 This, in itself, suggests that the parties in the deliberative stage of the original position will have an overriding interest in the distribution of primary goods.12 This impression is confirmed by Rawls's account of the reasoning behind the two principles of justice, especially that of the difference principle. According to Rawls the benchmark position in the deliberative stage is one of complete equality in the distribution of primary goods (TJ p62, PL p282). From this position, departures from equality are considered, both in “organisational powers” - an undefined term - and the distribution of wealth and income (TJ p62). Where these inequalities work to the benefit of the least-advantaged representative person, they ought to be permitted.13 The extent of inequality permitted is determined by the point at which greater inequality fails to improve the lot of the least-advantaged.14 8 Euclidean geometry is a pure axiomatic system; replace the geometrical terms consistently in the postulates with nonsense syllables and the system still 'works' in that all the conclusions are logically valid. If 'persons' is replaced by 'booyangs' throughout TJ or PL, the result is morass of pointless verbiage. It is the fact that his argument is intended to be in some way descriptive, and applicable to the world, which makes Rawls's endeavour something different in kind from pure axiomatic systems like geometry. 9 An interesting case concerns the objective circumstances, and the assumption of moderate scarcity. On what basis is this known to be true? Reflection on the history of human societies seems to imply that an imbalance between demands and the extent of the social product is the norm, but is this to be taken therefore as an enduring 'fact' about all societies past, present and future? Why must it be true that scarcity will prevail? This 'fact' is in reality an inductive argument with no particular claim to universal truth. This observation does not commit us to the Utopian proposition that scarcity definitely can be eliminated, but rather it points to the fact that Rawls bases his “moral geometry ” not on facts per se, but, in this case, on an argument taken at face value. 10 The case of the OCJ is taken up in detail by Bradford (2000a). 11 This is especially evident when he endeavours to encapsulate the meaning of the circumstances of justice. Thus, “one can say, in brief, that the circumstances of justice obtain whenever mutually disinterested persons put forward conflicting claims to the division of social advantages under conditions of moderate scarcity” (TJ p128), and, “justice is the virtue of practices where there are competing interests and where people feel entitled to press their rights on each other” (TJ p129). 12 Rawls speaks of the basic structure distributing primary goods, but it is clear that this is true only of a subset (TJ p62). Rights and liberties are part of the 'skeleton' of the basic structure, being guaranteed to all via the constitution and just legislation. Thus the distributive aspect of the basic structure comprises the mechanics of wealth and income distribution, and the means whereby powers and opportunities (the worth of liberty) are shared out. Clearly the former is the most important with respect to discussions of the difference principle, and therefore to the central theme of this paper. 13 Rawls ties the welfare of the least-advantaged to that of all other groups in society by means of the 7 When turning to a more detailed discussion of this point, Rawls acknowledges that the meaning of a departure from distributional equality being to 'everyone's advantage' is open to several interpretations (TJ p65). He therefore considers a variety of interpretations of the Second Principle (TJ pp. 65-83). The common thread running through all of these is what Rawls calls the “principle of efficiency” (TJ pp. 67-68). This is none other than the familiar concept of Pareto optimality, suitably modified to apply to the basic structure rather than the allocation of a stock of commodities among a group of individuals. The system of Natural Liberty is the libertaria n model of society. With careers open to those with the talent and desire to strive for them, the distribution of wealth, income and authority is determined by the principle of efficiency, in the context of a free market system, and the result deemed just. The system of Liberal Equality is an attempt to counter the moral arbitrariness of Natural Liberty by insisting on fair, and not simply formal, equality of opportunity in the pursuit of social positions. In this way the contingencies of social fortune are countered, and the resulting Pareto optimal distribution reflects the underlying distribution of natural abilities. The system of Democratic Equality combines fair equality of opportunity with the difference principle. In effect, the just distribution is that Pareto optimum which satisfies first the condition that it has been achieved through fair equality of opportunity, and second that the expectations of the least-advantaged representative person are maximised.15 Rawls obviously concludes that this interpretation is to be preferred and presented to the parties in the deliberative stage. Thus, in line with the 'competing claims' aspect of the SCJ, the reasoning for the principles of justice is based squarely on consideration of the distribution of primary goods, and not at all on the manner in which they are to be produced. The underlying reason for this is straightforward: Rawls assumes that the parties in the deliberative stage accept the Pareto principle as the yardstick by which to judge the efficiency of social and economic arrangements (TJ p67). Pagano (1985) demonstrates convincingly that modern general equilibrium theory, and thus its associated welfare economics, relies on the assumption that work assumption of chain connection (TJ pp. 81-82). This principle entails that, at least over a certain range, the welfare of the various socioeconomic 'groups' (from 'best-off' to 'worst-off') does not display mutual independence. Specifically, anything that improves the situation of the worst-off can be relied upon to do the same for the better-off, and vice versa . As a result, departures from the complete-equality benchmark can be considered either to everyone's advantage or not, depending upon their effect on the least-advantaged. Barry (1973 pp. 110-11) labels chain connection “a sort of living fossil, a coelacanth among ideas ” and notes that it instantly knocks the bottom out of most possible issues concerning the distribution of desirable but scarce resources of the kind which have given an edge to political dispute in the past few millennia. Rawls explicitly declines to examine the likelihood that chain connection will, or does, hold (ibid.). 14 Rawls acknowledges the index-number problem associated with assessing the welfare of the least- advantaged based on different 'baskets' of primary goods (TJ pp. 93-5). What he does not comment on, however, is exactly how the parties in the deliberative stage know that an unequal distribution impacts upon the welfare of the least-advantaged. How is it that they are aware of the mechanism through which more for some makes others better off? They have neither information about the nature of their society nor any about themselves or any other individual. They do have access to the principles of social, political and economic theory, but it is hard to see how the required inferences could be made in the absence of more detailed empirical information. 15 These are expectations of realising their conception of the good, which are dependent on the bundle of primary goods received. 8 enters the preference structure of economic agents only in regard to the amount of labour supplied by the individual, and not in relation to the nature of the tasks performed. This aspect of orthodox theory is rooted in Walras's treatment of labour whereby the labour supply of an individual is divided into two parts. One part is sold for use in the production of consumer goods or consumption services, while the remaining part is 'consumed' by the individual him(her)self. This latter part has subsequently been labelled 'leisure' (or some utility-producing 'reservation activity') and is assumed to yield utility to the individual, while that part of available labour which is dedicated to the production of consumer goods is assumed to have no impact on the welfare of the individual concerned.16 Thus the disutility of labour supply consists only of the opportunity cost of the number of hours worked in terms of foregone leisure. The use of the 'leisure device' implies that workers are indifferent to their conditions of work and the nature of the tasks they are to undertake; 8 hours working in a sewage treatment plant is therefore a no less desirable prospect than the equivalent amount of time spent working as a photographer of supermodels. Consumption goods and leisure time are the only ends desired by these agents, and work is regarded purely as a homogeneous means to these ends. Pagano demonstrates these implications more formally in the context of an orthodox resource allocation model. 17 He shows that when the social welfare function is dependent on the output vector of goods only, where leisure is a good produced by a reservation activity, technical efficiency is a necessary condition for social welfare maximisation. The optimisation problem can be broken down into two independent steps. First, purely as an engineering problem, the set of efficient vectors is identified; the quantity of manpower available to each firm is allocated among productive uses in such a way that more of one commodity can only be produced if the output of at least one other is reduced. Once this is achieved, preferences over output are considered in order to identify the efficient vector which maximises social welfare. In other words, as preferences over the organisation of production - that is, the allocation of tasks among jobs - play no part in the determination of the efficient production vectors, social welfare is invariant to the allocation of manpower within firms. This result holds both for capitalist firms and the single-firm centrally-planned economy. Under both regimes there is the possibility of rational conflict over the distribution of output, but none whatever over the organisation of production as the latter affects no individual's welfare. Now let us return to Rawls and the SCJ. If attention is focussed on the 'economic' primary goods (wealth and income) it is clear that the 'competing claims' aspect of the SCJ emphasised by Rawls is just another means of expressing the orthodox economic 16 For example, Koopmans (1957 p73n), Rawls's main reference for economic theory, acknowledges the need to introduce “artificial commodity concepts ”: “if labor is a primary input but leisure a desired commodity, one may introduce ‘man-hours ’ as a primary commodity and have its use as labor in actual production compete with its use in a ‘process’ which converts ‘man-hours ’ into an equal number of desired ‘leisure-hours ’”. 17 In Pagano's model the production function is defined over the vector of tasks. A task is understood to be a “use of manpower in production” described by a specification of the work to be done, how it is to done, and the time permitted for its execution (1985 p118). From the definition of tasks are derived the definitions of a job and a skill. The former is a subset of tasks to be performed by one unit of manpower within a particular firm, and thus represents the organisation of production within the firm. A skill is the resource endowment of an individual worker, defined as the set of tasks that the individual unit of manpower is able to perform. 9 assumption that preferences over work do not enter the social welfare function, that distribution, not production, is the prime concern. 18 This flies in the face of Rawls's insistence that he would not impose constraints on the conceptions of the good that are held (though unknown) by the parties in the deliberative stage. Apparently they are not to include the characteristics of the work they perform among the things they will value beyond the veil of ignorance. Furthermore, given that the parties must possess some kind of general awareness of the nature of human life and experience, the assumption that the quality and enjoyability of work is to be accorded no importance whatever is a strong and startling one to make.19 This is in direct conflict with Rawls's claim that the case for justice as fairness is based on “widely shared and yet weak conditions” and assumes “as little as possible” (TJ p129). Rawls appears to have flouted his own methodological prescriptions. This inconsistency notwithstanding, Rawls faces more fundamental difficulties arising out of his version of the SCJ. Pagano (op.cit.) reveals that implicit in resource allocation models which exclude preferences over work is the principle that de-skilling of jobs is conducive to the achievement of higher levels of social welfare.20 Within the framework of Pagano's model, de-skilling entails the redefinition of jobs within the production process of a firm (set of tasks to be performed) such that the number of tasks comprising at least one job is reduced, without an increase in the tasks comprising any of 18 It is fair to assume that Rawls is aware of this assumption and its role in orthodox theory, as it is mentioned at least twice in the section from Koopmans to which Rawls refers on the question of the principle of efficiency. There Koopmans notes that the optimality results of neoclassical theory require that “the satisfaction of each consumer is affected only by his own consumption and work, and not in addition by other people's consumption or by any production processes except through the fact that he contributes labor” (Koopmans 1957 p41, emphasis added). Later Koopmans reiterates that the proof of the allocative efficiency of a competitive market organisation depends in part on the assumption of the “independence of any man's [sic] preference structure from any production process ”(p53). 19 Given the history of industrial relations in the United States, marked as it is by outbreaks of violent and often fatal conflict over the organisation of production, it is a patently absurd assumption for Rawls to make. The historical record on this issue also poses some interesting questions with respect to the constitutional and legislative stages. When historical information is made available in these stages, facts of this nature, common to most industrialised countries, will presumably become known. Would we not expect this to influence any decisions regarding the ownership of the means of production? If, historically, capitalism has been characterised by violent struggles between the owners of the means of production and those whose labour they purchase, is that not a good reason to consider alternative property rights arrangements? Rawls's reliance on historical dominance implies that historical forms will be perpetuated despite past failings; at no time does he explicitly acknowledge the possibility that a wholesale change of regime may be required by the principles of justice. A more important question involves the extent to which information about individual conceptions of the good may be inferred from the historical information available in the later stages of the original position. If the parties become aware that many individuals have risked death and injury in the name of workplace reform and workers' rights, is it not reasonable to assume that they will infer, correctly, that the quality of work is an important element of the conception of the good of at leas t some persons? Once this step is taken, however, it is hard to see how the issue of the form of the basic structure would not become extremely important in the original position. More fundamentally still, once the parties have deduced that the organisation of production features in conceptions of the good, would they not consider Rawls's account of the SCJ to be incomplete and inaccurate? As the SCJ are one of the empirical constraints on the deliberative stage, this situation would necessitate a revaluation of the principles of justice in light of the new information. 20 As Pagano explains, this idea is rooted in pre-neoclassical thought. Gioia argued that a detailed division of labour would yield savings on training time, and thus be of benefit to society as a whole. Babbage maintained that the 'master manufacturer' could, assuming wages proportional to the skill requirements of jobs, realise cost savings by breaking complex and demanding tasks down into skilled and unskilled components. James Mill held that the Babbage principle should be extended to society as a whole in order to enhance social welfare through increased production of consumption goods. 10 the remaining jobs. As de-skilling enlarges the set of employable skills in an economy, it eases skill constraints and permits an increase in output from given manpower inputs. Given a social preference structure defined over goods only, this implies that de-skilling can only increase social welfare, or at least leave it unchanged (Pagano 1985 pp. 122- 126). Since the set of feasible output vectors for an individual firm remains feasible after de-skilling, while new vectors may be attainable, the process of de-skilling cannot decrease profits. Pagano states that the conclusion that can be derived from the resource allocation model is that the internal allocation of manpower will be organised by a profit-maximising manager according to the criterion that the de-skilling of jobs is never disadvantageous and that such an organisation of manpower is consistent with the aim of improving social welfare (ibid.). Moving beyond pure economic theory, these conclusions are also supported strongly by the labour process theory literature, particularly Braverman (1974). Braverman focuses on the implications of Taylorism, or 'scientific management' as an extension of the Gioia-Babbage principle. He isolates three main principles of Taylorism - the dissociation of the labour process from the skills of the workers, the separation of the conception and execution of tasks, and the use of management's knowledge of the productive process to plan and control production in a stepwise process - and argues that their widespread implementation in the capitalist mode of production reflects the necessity of control over the labour process under capitalism. Control is necessary if capitalists are to realise the potential of purchased labour power, impose their will within the social relations of production, and lower production costs (increase profits) by rendering labour more homogeneous. He concludes that the proliferation of Tayloristic control mechanisms has resulted in a destruction of all-round skills and the degradation of work. Braverman updates Marx's analysis of the labour process by examining the degradation of work in the history of twentieth-century industrialisation. As much of the labour process literature is also based extensively on historical information - for example, Marglin (1974) - the conclusions therein would presumably become known in the legislative stage, when the decision regarding the ownership of the means of production is meant to be made. Since the conclusions reached are scarcely flattering to capitalism, it would seem that Rawls is required to explain why historical dominance holds in the face of such information. If historical material of this nature is to be excluded from the legislative stage, Rawls must explain the criteria that differentiate 'acceptable' facts about the past from those that are 'unacceptable'. Without such explanations, Rawls's conclusions seem to be ultimately little more than an elaborate expression of his personal beliefs. Thompson (1989) notes that many within the literature on labour process theory have criticised what they see as the inexorable trend toward de-skilling implied by Braverman. 21 He acknowledges the importance of national differences in the development of the labour process (particularly with respect to the Japanese experience), the impact of flexible specialisation and the associated trend toward multiskilling and the recombination of intellectual and manual skills, and the incidence of both worker resistance to control and cooperation in the re-shaping of the labour process. 21 For example, see the papers collected in Wood (1982). 11 He concludes, however, by noting that the rejection of a uni-dimensional version of the Braverman thesis does not thereby negate the important conclusions of the labour process literature. When, as under capitalism, the capacity to work is utilised as a means of producing value, the logic of accumulation forces a constant revision of the labour process in order to accommodate the competition between units of capital, and the antagonism between capital and labour that characterises the capitalist mode of production. Linked to this is a control imperative; structures of control over labour are necessary if legal ownership of the means of production is to be translated into real possession. Neither of these principles imply that simple de-skilling is their only possible manifestation; capitalists will engage in flexible strategies which can incorporate re- skilling and the ceding of selected areas of responsibility and control. Overall, however, the need to retain general directive control over labour, and to satisfy the demands of accumulation, implies that both the use of workers' individual creative capacities, and attempts to dismantle hierarchical relations, must play a limited role in the capitalist labour process. The problem that the theoretical results of Pagano and labour process theory pose for Rawls concerns his account of the rationality of the parties in the original position, the so-called ‘thin theory of the good’. Rawls considers that a person's good is determined by the rational plan of life that he/she would choose with deliberative rationality from the maximal class of plans (TJ p424).22 A life-plan is seen as a hierarchy of sub-plans reflecting a procession of desires from more to less general. Although plans cover the whole of an individual's life, the details of the various sub-plans decrease the further they are away from the present.23 Rational plans are those which most efficiently match means and ends, and encompass the results of other plans (Rawls calls the latter the principle of inclusiveness). Rawls insists that the theory of the good must be 'thin', meaning that ideas of human excellences, and other specifications of what ought to be wanted, should not be incorporated into the definition of rationality. Yet without some restriction on the content of rationa l plans, Rawls's argument is in danger of collapsing into a kind of utilitarianism; the good for an individual simply becomes getting more of what he/she wants (Barry 1973 p30). In such a situation, there is no reason for the parties in the deliberative stage to focus on the primary goods as the things to be distributed. As a result, the solution to their choice problem (deciding on 22 The concept of deliberative rationality, which Rawls ascribes to Sidgwick, is in essence a state of perfect foresight with respect to the outcomes of plans. The problems associated with defining 'goodness' for parties in the original position with reference to the case where all future outcomes are known need little elaboration. The parallel with the role of perfect foresight assumptions in (much) neoclassical theory is intriguing. 23 There are interesting similarities between Rawls's device of rational plans and Koopmans's discussion of the interpretation of the competitive general equilibrium model with respect to time. Rawls has the conception of the good determined by the rational life plan that he/she would choose with deliberative rationality from the maximal class of plans (TJ p424). A life-plan is seen as a hierarchy of sub-plans reflecting a procession of desires from more to less general. Although plans cover the whole of an individual's life, the details of the various sub-plans decrease the further they are away from the present. Koopmans notes that when time is divided into successive periods and commodities dated, the choice of a consumer is in fact “a plan for future consumption extending over all periods considered”. Furthermore “[the consumer's] preference ordering is thought of as an ordering of all such plans”. Koopmans (1957 p61) admits that uncertainty is excluded from the model: “[c]onsumers choose a plan for their lifetime, in full present knowledge of their future preferences, of the time of their death, and of the place occupied in their preference structure by the resources handed on at death to their heirs”. Rawls does not acknowledge any debt to Koopmans, nor is any suggested, but it is intriguing to consider that the thin theory of the good may be based in part on some aspects of intertemporal general equilibrium theory. 12 principles of justice) is indeterminate; the argument for justice as fairness stalls at the outset. Since the parties in the deliberative stage are assumed not to know the details of their conception of the good, Rawls is forced to introduce an empirical generalisation about human psychology that is to be known in the original position, and which will imply that rationality entails desiring the primary goods. This is the Aristotelian Principle: ceteris paribus, humans enjoy the exercise of their innate and trained capacities, and this enjoyment is proportional to the extent of the capacity utilised and the degree of complexity required (TJ p414). For example, a person who can play both draughts and chess would prefer the latter. From this Rawls concludes that humans prefer a larger pattern of ends (in order to utilise capacities more intensively) and that plans will reflect this in that comprehensive plans will be preferred.24 In other words, humans have a higher-order desire to follow the principle of inclusiveness. For Rawls, the Aristotelian Principle is a theory of motivation that accounts for our major desires and preferences (TJ p428). By ordering all human activities in interdependent chains according to the principle of inclusiveness - such that the nth activity in a given chain encompasses all of the skills required for the (n-1)th - the Aristotelian Principle can be reformulated as the assertion that humans always desire to move up chains. In fact, in a manner sure to please any neo-classical economist, humans will apply their available resources (in terms of time and energy devoted to development) to moving up the chains associated with any preferred pattern of activities to the point where no benefit is to gained from rearrangement (TJ p431). The role of the Aristotelian Principle in the thin theory of the good is, according to Rawls, that it states a deep psychological fact which, in conjunction with other general facts and the conception of a rational plan, accounts for our considered judgements of value. The things that are commonly thought of as human goods should turn out to be the ends and activities that have a major place in rational plans. The principle is part of the background that regulates these judgements (TJ p432). The question of the relationship between the thin theory of the good, centred on the Aristotelian Principle, and the rationality of desiring primary goods is unclear.25 In 24 Note the difficulty associated with the fact that it is the content of rational plans (or specifically the plan which would be chosen with deliberative rationality) which defines the good for a person. What then is the basis for preference between plans? How can we make sense of the claim that comprehensive plans are 'better' than simple plans? It cannot be that they produce more 'goodness', as that would be circular. 25 Rawls himself seems undecided of the truth of the Principle and indeed whether or not it needs to be true in the context of his theory. On page 427 he claims that there is no reason to explain why it is true. After introducing some casual, anecdotal 'evidence', he concludes that the issue is unimportant for the theory of the good. On page 429 the Principle has become a tendency rather than an invariable pattern, one which could be overridden by the costs of training. Two pages later Rawls alludes to evolution to support the Principle, and holds that the important point is to illustrate its role in the formulation of rational plans given that it is true. On page 432 he makes the truth of the Principle a condition for it having a proper role in moral theory, despite having just declared that it expresses a “deep psychological fact“. He then goes on to state that even if the Principle is not universally true, the idea of rational plans as the determinants of goodness is still valid. He strengthens this claim on the next page by holding that the correctness of defining goodness in terms of rational plans does not require the truth of the Aristotelian Principle at all. In fact it is defensible on instrumental grounds as by assuming it we can explain why certain things have been recognised as goods. Moreover, it has a central role to play in the moral psychology upon which the theory of justice as fairness is based. Economists will be reminded at this point of Hicks's (1946 p84) admission that the main reason for maintaining the 13 fact, Rawls declines to make the case, claiming that the relationship is “evident enough” (TJ p434). The impression given by the arguments for goodness as rationality is that the primary goods are means to virtually all ends, and since the Aristotelian Principle implies that rational plans will be those which include the widest possible diversity of ends, it follows that rational parties in the original position would wish to secure as large an amount of primary goods for themselves as possible. Thus, as a motivational assumption, the Aristotelian Principle explains the desire for primary goods in the deliberative stage. Unfortunately, it conflicts with the implications of the economic and social theory presumed known in that stage. Given that they know humans enjoy exercising their abilities, how will the parties react to the fact that the logic of capitalist production requires the de-skilling of jobs, and thus the retardation of those skills, the work-related skills, utilised most intensively throughout a human life?26 If the Aristotelian Principle is indeed a theory of motivation that accounts for our major desires and preferences (TJ p428), why would the implications of capitalist ownership and control mechanisms, with regard to de- skilling and the maintenance of authoritarian and hierarchical relations within production, not result in the question of the organisation of production taking a prominent place in the discussions of the deliberative stage?27 This conclusion is strengthened by the psychological evidence, cited by Bowles and Gintis (1976), Ryan (1981) and Schwartz (1982), to the effect that participation in monotonous, routine activity is damaging to cognitive performance in general. Thus the process of de-skilling could be held to lead to a general deterioration in the ability of workers to exercise their capacities in any and all of the activities in which they engage.28 Awareness of this potential effect of capitalist employer behaviour represents an avenue through which the assignment of property rights over the means of production could affect the development of the “sufficient material basis for a sense of personal independence and self-respect” that Rawls holds to be essential for the development of the two moral powers (PL p298). Possession of the two moral powers is held by Rawls to be a necessary and sufficient condition for being regarded as a “full and equal member of society” with respect to questions of political justice, and thus is central to the development of self-respect, the most important of primary goods (PL p302). As such, the definition of rationality for the parties in the assumption of perfect competition is that the coherence of equilibrium theory requires it. For further criticism of the Aristotelian Principle see Barry (1973). 26 The importance of these skills is acknowledged by Rawls, at one remove, when he identifies the choice of occupation with the choice of a life-plan and conception of the sort of person to be (TJ pp. 415-16). 27 Strictly speaking, de-skilling is an outcome of profit-maximisation or some other behaviour, the outcomes of which are identical to those that obtain from profit-maximising behaviour. For this reason Rawls's reference (TJ p271n) to Vanek (1970), intended to establish the equivalence of perfect competition and perfect socialism and thus provide support for Rawls's concentration on distribution, appears to be unhelpful. Pagano (1985 p174) relates that the Ward-Vanek-Meade models of self- managed firms assume that the members of workers' cooperatives attempt to maximise income per head without reference to the utility derived from work. As a result, the self-managed firm will allocate labour, and be managed, according to the same criteria as if a profit-maximising capitalist were at the helm. However, this contention itself would appear to apply only to the ‘dehumanised’ model of Part I of Vanek (1970) where effort intensity and labour quality are assumed constant and equal. In his subsequent analysis Vanek drops these assumptions and argues that the labour-managed firm will be more responsive to the desires of its members than capital-managed firms. Although Vanek does not explicitly mention preferences over work, the effects of the democratisation of the division of labour would seem to counter Pagano’s assertion. 28 Capacities that could conceivably include those related to the second moral power – the capacity to form, revise and pursue a conception of the good. 14 deliberative stage would encompass an interest in the ownership status of the means of production. Difficulties and Remedies If this were to occur, however, Rawls's argument comes apart in a number of crucial places. First, it is unclear how the central focus on the primary goods could be justified in this context. Second, the difference principle could no longer be defined in relation to the principle of efficiency; the parties in the deliberative stage would no longer be satisfied merely with considering deviations from a benchmark of an equal distribution of primary goods, as the form of the basic structure would be an important, relevant consideration. A new method of justification is required. Third, the problems associated with the specification of the basic liberties would be intensified, as there seems to be no obvious reason to exclude social property in the means of production from the list. Yet allowing its inclusion implies that it should be incorporated into the just constitution. This would have the effect of negating Rawls's conceptual division of the basic structure into 'political' and 'economic' sections, and, more fundamentally, would undermine the priority rules of justice as fairness whereby political justice is lexically prior to equality of opportunity which is lexically prior to the justice of economic distribution. In light of these disastrous consequences, how can Rawls respond? Unfortunately, given the structure of the argument in TJ, his options are limited. Altering his account of the SCJ so as to take account of preferences over work is not a feasible option. Pagano (1985 p126-29) shows that when workers' preferences over tasks are included in the social welfare function, the manpower allocations of profit-maximising firms need not be conducive to social welfare maximisation.29 As de-skilling can now result in a decrease in social welfare, the derivation of the optimum output vector can no longer be decomposed into a two-stage procedure beginning with the isolation of efficient vectors, conceived as an engineering problem. Hence, Rawls could no longer employ the principle of efficiency in deriving the difference principle and he would have to recast his entire argument, taking into account the subsequent interest the parties in the deliberative stage would have in the organisation of production. The dilemma facing Rawls may be put as follows. If he maintains his account of the SCJ and ignores preferences over work, then the conflict between the Aristotelian Principle and the de- skilling implications of economic theory renders untenable arguments based on the principle of efficiency, as the parties will not accept simple comparisons of distributions only. If he repudiates his version of the SCJ and recognises the welfare implications of work, the principle of efficiency ceases to be operative and thus cannot be utilised in deriving the principles of justice. As the inconsistency between the SCJ and the Aristotelian Principle is at the root of Rawls's difficulties, he could utilise another principle of motivation. Although he acknowledges in PL (p203n) that other, unspecified, psychological principles could yield the same results, it is not really possible to deduce the ramifications of such a move for Rawls's system. It is worth noting, however, that in PL (pp. 203, 207) Rawls indicates 29 Thurow (1980-81) employs the concept of “psychic income ” to derive the same conclusion and argue that capitalist work organisation represents a case of market failure . In a perspicacious treatment of the issue, Sen (1975) demonstrates the problems posed for assessments of ‘efficiency’ by the existence of worker preferences relating to both tasks and alternative techniques. Albert and Hahnel (1991 p19 ) argue that tasks that are “employee empowering” in their effects will be undersupplied, and paid less than the socially optimal wage, under capitalism, thus generating a form of market failure. 15 that the Aristotelian Principle is central to the case for the goodness of the well-ordered society of justice as fairness. The link is through the exercise of the two moral powers, which are interpreted as examples of the kind of capacities to which the Aristotelian Principle refers. Hence certain key aspects of Rawls's program seem to be dependent on the particular moral psychology represented by the Aristotelian Principle. Buchanan (1982 pp. 123-124) suggests that Rawls could evade the difficulties outlined above, with respect to the SCJ, by including 'meaningful' work as one of the social bases of self-respect, the most important of the primary goods. However, this defence is unreliable for several reasons. First, Rawls holds that the definition of meaningful work is not a problem of justice (TJ p290). As such, there seems to be little scope for incorporating it into the list of primary goods. In any case, Buchanan offers no account of how the thin theory of the good, as it stands, provides a justification for considering 'meaningful' work to be a primary good. Nor does he explain how the reasoning for the principles of justice could incorporate the link to the organisation of production implicit in a definition of rationality that refers in part to a desire for 'meaningful' work. In short, Buchanan may wish to espouse a mutant form of Rawls's argument, but Rawls cannot. Second, although Rawls identifies 'meaningful' work as one of the 'human goods' (TJ p425), it is clear from the context that it is an end rather than a means.30 As such, including it among the primary goods serves only to make the thin theory of the good appreciably 'thicker', a state of affairs precluded by Rawls's methodology. Third, it seems a rather ad hoc procedure to simply enlarge the list of primary goods whenever a critic points out lacunæ in the argument. If the concept of primary goods is to be useful, then surely the list of primary goods must be a limited subset of all possible goods. If the two are coextensive, then justice as fairness becomes utilitarianism. If most goods are considered primary then the coherence of the thin theory of the good is endangered. Rawls himself is guilty of the sin of multiplying the primary goods without necessity. When replying to Musgrave (1974) on a point concerning optimal taxation, defensive goods-leisure substitutions and the institutions of the just society, Rawls (1974 p654) indicates that leisure may be included in the list of primary goods. The problem with this case is that the basic structure is held by Rawls to distribute the primary goods. If leisure is construed as a strictly private activity, as in mainstream economic theory, then it is not distributed by the major social and economic institutions, or anything else.31 However, not regarding leisure as a private activity in that sense would require attention to the organisation of production, as it is the economic institutions that will 'distribute' leisure through their impact on required work time. Finally, the link to self-respect is not as obvious as it seems on the basis of 'commonsense' psychology. For Rawls, self-respect is derived not from interpersonal experiences directly, but from knowledge of the justice of the basic structure. Hence, by securing the basic rights and liberties for all, and guaranteeing fair equality of opportunity, the just society underwrites the “essentials of persons' public recognition as free and equal citizens” (PL p203). This state of affairs secures the fundamental needs of citizens and establishes the social bases of self-respect. Clearly, there are few prospects for integrating 'meaningful' work into such a conception of self-respect. In presenting the next possible line of defence, it should be noted that Rawls is aware of the less desirable implications of the capitalist labour process, and, indeed, he feels they would be inappropriate in the just society. He declares that: 30 Rawls states elsewhere that “what men want is meaningful work in free association with others, these associations regulating their relations to one another within a framework of just institutions” (TJ p290). 31 Private in the sense that it involves a given, private ‘reservation activity’. 16 a well-ordered society does not do away with the division of labor in the most general sense. To be sure, the worst aspects of this division can be surmounted: no one need be servilely dependent on others and made to choose between monotonous and routine occupations which are deadening to human thought and sensibility. Each can be offered a variety of tasks so that the different elements of his nature find a suitable expression (TJ p529). The sentime nt is welcome, but Rawls provides no explanation as to how the monotonous jobs will be replaced by stimulating and rewarding ones in the just society. Barry (1973 pp. 163-165) is probably correct when he suggests that Rawls believes that ensuring the freedom of choice of occupation, and full employment through the stabilisation branch, will suffice to make work meaningful. If this were so, then Rawls could evade the criticisms made above. He certainly argues that, in equilibrium, the attractiveness of jobs will be equalised (TJ p305). This ties in with his partiality to the property-owning democracy of Meade (1964). Meade waxes utopian about the way in which work would become purely voluntary in such a system (exit would be costless).32 But since the characteristics of jobs are out of the control of workers it seems there is no mechanism to ensure that jobs are meaningful. 33 Such an outcome may be possible if jobs covering all conceivable combinations of tasks were available under conditions of continuous full employment. Given the difficulty of achieving the latter conditions under capitalism, and the fact that the imperatives of control and accumulation make it unlikely that all superseded production methods would coexist with their replacements, this seems a most unhelpful straw at which to clutch. Rawls's final, and most feeble, retort is methodological in character. He argues that common understanding in the original position requires bounds on the complexity of theoretical arguments permitted there (TJ p142). Although it is difficult to grade general facts on the basis of complexity, he holds that we “recognise an intricate theoretical construction” easily enough. On these grounds, he supposes that conceptions of justice which depend on simpler general facts, and which require less trawling through theoretically defined possibilities, are to be preferred. That the author of the 582 pages of argument which constitute TJ could put forward this proposition without apparent irony is, to put it mildly, quite surprising, but in any case it is somewhat hypocritical to reject the above criticisms on the ground that they require excessive theoretical manipulation. At root, the criticisms rest on aspects of the very theories that Rawls calls upon to justify his own argument. Besides, whether or not the economics of Koopmans is considered an ‘intricate theoretical construction’, it is certainly no more so than the argument for justice as fairness itself. Conclusion Ultimately, Rawls is left with no viable defence to the charge that the neglect of production in favour of distribution in his system stems from his 'competing claims' account of the SCJ, which in turn reflects the assumption of neo-classical economic theory that social welfare and technical efficiency are independent of preferences over work. The implications of the SCJ clash with the psychological premises upon which the rationality of parties in the original position is based, and thus deprive Rawls's 32 Bradford (2000b) examines the relationship between Rawls and Meade in greater detail. 33 Perhaps the orthodox model assumes that jobs, like consumption goods, have only one characteristic - in this case 'jobness'? 17 conclusions of logical support. One or the other must go, but modifying the SCJ (retreating from the 'competing claims' interpretation and taking account of preferences over the organisation of production) means ditching the principle of efficiency and therefore the argument for the principles of justice, particularly the difference principle. Thus Rawls appears committed to retaining his account of the SCJ if he is to preserve, at least superficially, the integrity of his argument. This leaves him in the awkward position of maintaining that the parties in the original position will focus on distribution, and ignore the form of the basic structure, only on the basis of a strong assumption that represents a prior constraint on possible conceptions of the good in violation of his own methodological dicta. 18 References Albert, M. and Hahmel, R. (1991) The Political Economy of Participatory Economics (Princeton, Princeton University Press). Barry, B. (1973) The Liberal Theory of Justice (Oxford, Clarendon). Bowles, S., and Gintis, H. (1976) Schooling in Capitalist America: Educational Reform and the Contradictions of Economic Life (New York, Basic Books). Bradford, W.D. (2000a) Value and Justice: Property, Economic Theory and Rawls (Doctoral Dissertation, University of Cambridge). _____ (2000b) “Rawls and Meade: Unfortunate Bedfellows?”, Macquarie Economics Research Papers 8/2000 (Sydney, Macquarie University). Braverman, H. (1974) Labor and Monopoly Capital: The Degradation of Work in the Twentieth Century (London, Monthly Review Press). Buchanan, A. (1982) Marx and Justice: The Radical Critique of Liberalism (London, Methuen). Hicks, J.R. (1946) Value and Capital: An Inquiry into Some Fundamental Principles of Economic Theory (Oxford, Clarendon Press). Koopmans, T.C. (1957) Three Essays on the State of Economic Science (New York, McGraw-Hill). Marglin, S.A. (1974) “What do Bosses Do? The Origins and Functions of Hierarchy in Capitalist Production”, Review of Radical Political Economics, 6, pp. 60-112. Meade, J.E. (1964) Efficiency, Equality and the Ownership of Property (London, Allen and Unwin). Musgrave, R.A. (1974) “Maximin, Uncertainty, and the Leisure Trade-Off”, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 88, pp. 625-32. Pagano, U. (1985) Work and Welfare in Economic Theory (Oxford, Basil Blackwell). Parkin, M. and Norbay, A.R. (1975) Contemporary Issues In Economics (Manchester, Manchester University Press). Rawls, J. (1971) A Theory of Justice (Oxford, Oxford University Press). _____ (1974) “Reply to Alexander and Musgrave”, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 88, pp. 633-55. _____ (1993) Political Liberalism (New York, Columbia University Press). Ryan, W. (1981) Equality (New York, Pantheon Books). 19 Sandel, M.J. (1982) Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press). Schwartz, A. (1982) “Meaningful Work”, Ethics, 92, pp. 634-46. Sen, A.K. (1975) “The Concept of Efficiency” in Parkin and Norbay (1975). Thompson, P. (1989) The Nature of Work: An Introduction to Debates on the Labour Process 2ed (London, MacMillan) Thurow, L. (1980-81) “Psychic Income: A Market Failure”, Journal of Post Keynesian Economics, 3, pp. 183-93. Vanek, J. (1970) The General Theory of Labor-Managed Market Economies (Ithaca, Cornell University Press). Wood, S. (ed) (1982) The Degradation of Work? Skill, Deskilling and the Labour Process (London, Hutchinson). work_gc6tzyav7jfrdmn2mgboeine7e ---- wp-p1m-39.ebi.ac.uk Params is empty 404 sys_1000 exception wp-p1m-39.ebi.ac.uk no 221735940 Params is empty 221735940 exception Params is empty 2021/04/06-03:20:34 if (typeof jQuery === "undefined") document.write('[script type="text/javascript" src="/corehtml/pmc/jig/1.14.8/js/jig.min.js"][/script]'.replace(/\[/g,String.fromCharCode(60)).replace(/\]/g,String.fromCharCode(62))); // // // window.name="mainwindow"; .pmc-wm {background:transparent repeat-y top left;background-image:url(/corehtml/pmc/pmcgifs/wm-nobrand.png);background-size: auto, contain} .print-view{display:block} Page not available Reason: The web page address (URL) that you used may be incorrect. Message ID: 221735940 (wp-p1m-39.ebi.ac.uk) Time: 2021/04/06 03:20:33 If you need further help, please send an email to PMC. Include the information from the box above in your message. Otherwise, click on one of the following links to continue using PMC: Search the complete PMC archive. Browse the contents of a specific journal in PMC. Find a specific article by its citation (journal, date, volume, first page, author or article title). http://europepmc.org/abstract/MED/ work_gflym2t4z5gr7ao3ptxnuapxiq ---- untitled PAPER Justice and the NICE approach Richard Cookson Correspondence to Dr Richard Cookson, Centre for Health Economics, University of York, York YO10 5DD, UK; richard.cookson@york.ac.uk Received 5 September 2014 Revised 26 September 2014 Accepted 3 October 2014 To cite: Cookson R. J Med Ethics 2015;41:99–102. ABSTRACT When thinking about population level healthcare priority setting decisions, such as those made by the National Institute for Health and Care Excellence, good medical ethics requires attention to three main principles of health justice: (1) cost-effectiveness, an aspect of beneficence, (2) non-discrimination, and (3) priority to the worse off in terms of both current severity of illness and lifetime health. Applying these principles requires consideration of the identified patients who benefit from decisions and the unidentified patients who bear the opportunity costs. INTRODUCTION What is it to do good medical ethics? An uncharit- able reader of the philosophical medical ethics lit- erature might be forgiven for answering, ‘come up with an absurdly unrealistic example, and use it to argue for an absurdly counter-intuitive conclusion.’ This flippant remark is, of course, grossly unfair. Yet replace ‘absurdly’ with ‘appropriately’, and it describes two important virtues of ethical thinking. Unrealistic examples can help clarify our thinking by placing the essential features of an ethical problem into sharp focus. And common sense intuitions can lead us astray. Our moral psychology was shaped by evolution during millions of years of human prehistory living in small hunter-gatherer tribes. The resulting intuitions may sometimes lead us astray in today’s much larger and more techno- logically advanced societies. Rather than resting content with ‘fast thinking’ intuitions, therefore, it behoves us to engage in some ‘slow thinking’ to arrive at more considered ethical judgements.1 2 The medical ethics literature pays close attention to technological advances in medicine and how they raise new ethical challenges. However, it pays less attention to another important difference between hunter-gatherer and modern societies: size. Hunter-gather tribes rarely contained more than around 150 people—the ‘Dunbar number’, above which humans and primates find it hard to handle social relationships3—and everyone knew each other. By contrast, modern societies are vast and impersonal. National governments routinely make decisions that influence thousands, millions and in some cases even hundreds of millions of fellow citizens who do not know each other. Medical ethicists spend a lot of time discussing hypothetical examples involving a small number of identified patients. In this essay, I want to focus on population level decisions involving a large number of unidentified patients. My focus is not on clinical decisions about particular patients, but on policy decisions by healthcare managers and policymakers about the institutional, regulatory and financial environment within which such clinical decisions are made. A paradigmatic example is the National Institute for Health and Care Excellence (NICE). NICE pro- duces guidance on the use of healthcare technolo- gies within the single payer, universal and comprehensive National Health Service (NHS) in England and Wales. However, NICE has no control over the size of the tax-funded NHS budget or how local NHS organisations manage their budgets. When NICE recommends the use of a cost-increasing healthcare technology for one par- ticular group of patients, therefore, it is implicitly recommending the displacement of expenditure on unknown alternative uses of NHS money for unknown other patients. What principles of justice should govern such decisions about the allocation of scarce healthcare resources? I will sketch out the ‘NICE approach’ to this question—or, rather, my own interpretation of it—and argue that it embodies ‘good’ rather than ‘bad’ medical ethics. The starting point for NICE is the procedural justice framework that bioethicist Norman Daniels has dubbed ‘accountability for reasonableness’, with its four requirements of: (i) publicly accessible decisions and the rationales for them, (ii) reason- ableness of rationales in the sense both of giving reasons and applying relevant principles, (iii) the possibility of challenge through appeal and of revi- sion of decisions and (iv) the presence of mechan- isms to ensure that the foregoing requirements are met.4 Within this framework, NICE focuses on three substantive principles of justice: (1) cost- effectiveness, (2) non-discrimination and (3) prior- ity to the worse off.5 I will start with cost-effectiveness. COST-EFFECTIVENESS Should opportunity costs for large numbers of unidentified people be taken into account in health- care priority setting decisions? NICE thinks the answer is an unequivocal ‘yes’. It accounts for opportunity costs to unknown patients in exactly the same way that it accounts for benefits to the known patients who use the healthcare technology under consideration. It values these opportunity costs in terms of the expected impact on the length and quality of people’s lives using the ‘quality adjusted life year’ (QALY). One QALY represents 1 year of life in full health, half a QALY represents a year of life in 50% health and so on. NICE cur- rently estimates that a reduction of £20 000 pounds of NHS expenditure on unknown NHS activities benefiting unknown patients will typically Cookson R. J Med Ethics 2015;41:99–102. doi:10.1136/medethics-2014-102386 99 JME40: Good medical ethics o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://jm e .b m j.co m / J M e d E th ics: first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /m e d e th ics-2 0 1 4 -1 0 2 3 8 6 o n 1 6 D e ce m b e r 2 0 1 4 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1136/medethics-2014-102386&domain=pdf&date_stamp=2014-12-11 http://jme.bmj.com/ http://www.instituteofmedicalethics.org/website/ http://jme.bmj.com/ have an opportunity cost of one QALY. This is not far off the current best estimate of this ‘cost per QALY threshold value’ of £18 000, based on real data on variation in NHS expenditure and outcomes between subnational administrative areas (for- merly known as ‘Primary Care Trusts’ when the data were col- lected in 2008, and now ‘Clinical Commissioning Groups’).6 By using this estimate to value opportunity costs, NICE is making the value judgement that each QALY lost by unknown NHS patients has the same value as each QALY gained by the known group of patients who use the healthcare technology under consideration. This value judgement is a straightforward corollary of the principle of cost-effectiveness that healthcare resources should be used to improve population health. Stewards of the public purse have a duty of ‘beneficence’ towards all the citizens they serve, to do as much good as possible with scarce public resources. In the context of healthcare, it seems reasonable to interpret this as a duty to improve population health. This seems to be the UK government’s interpretation since it charges both NICE and the NHS with the objective of improving popu- lation health. How should ‘population health’ be measured? The value judgement made by NICE is that units of health should simply be added up across different citizens, on the basis that ‘a QALY is a QALY is a QALY’. It is thus assumed that a year or a day or indeed an hour of life in full health has the same value, no matter who lives it. A QALY thus the same value no matter whether it is lived by a known or an unknown group of citizens, no matter whether it is seen as a gain or a loss from the refer- ence point of the current situation, and no matter how many healthy years are gained or lost in total compared with the current situation. That value judgement is illustrated in figure 1. The horizontal x-axis shows the health opportunity cost in terms of the total number of QALYs lost by unknown patients. The vertical y-axis shows the total value of those health opportunity costs, accord- ing to NICE. It is a 45° straight line, reflecting the NICE value judgement that each QALY is worth the same. Psychic numbing The NICE approach contrasts sharply with the common sense intuitions embedded in our moral psychology. Drawing on evi- dence from psychological experiments, as well as the observations of social commentators and our own everyday experience, Paul Slovic7 has described the phenomenon of ‘psy- chophysical numbing’ and its more extreme cousin of ‘psychic numbing’. The psychology evidence typically focuses on health losses framed in terms of numbers of deaths; but the same idea can be applied to any numerical unit of health loss, including QALYs. Psychophysical numbing involves diminishing marginal concern for health losses. In that case, we care a lot about a single unit of health loss, but then a bit less about the next one, a bit less still about the next one and so on. This implies that our concern for an opportunity cost of 1000 QALYs is not much greater than our concern for an opportunity cost of 1 QALY, and nowhere near 1000 times greater as the NICE approach implies. Psychic numbing is more extreme, and involves diminishing total concern for health losses, as illu- strated in figure 2. In that case, we care more about a health loss of 1 QALY to a single identified person than about a health loss of 1 QALY each to 1000 unidentified people. Figure 3 compares the NICE approach with common sense ethical intuitions. When thinking about health opportunity costs to large numbers of unknown people, our common sense Figure 1 National Institute for Health and Care Excellence’s valuation of health opportunity costs. Figure 2 Public concern for health opportunity costs under psychic numbing. Figure 3 Compassion deficit—National Institute for Health and Care Excellence (NICE) valuation versus public concern under psychic numbing. 100 Cookson R. J Med Ethics 2015;41:99–102. doi:10.1136/medethics-2014-102386 JME40: Good medical ethics o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://jm e .b m j.co m / J M e d E th ics: first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /m e d e th ics-2 0 1 4 -1 0 2 3 8 6 o n 1 6 D e ce m b e r 2 0 1 4 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://jme.bmj.com/ intuitions result in what we might call a ‘compassion deficit’. We are capable of feeling a high degree of compassion about a health loss to a single identified person, but we are not capable of feeling thousands of times more compassion about health losses to thousands of unidentified people. Indeed, because our instincts evolved to feel compassion towards identifiable indivi- duals, we tend to feel more compassion for a single known indi- vidual than thousands of unidentified individuals. Crude utilitarianism? Does the NICE approach imply a crude utilitarianism that favours inhumane acts, for example, the callous neglect of severely ill patients who fail the cost-effectiveness test? Or ‘Brave New World’ style happiness pills for all, coupled with ‘Logan’s Run’ style involuntary euthanasia for the over 30s? Of course not! For one thing, QALYs measure health and longevity, not happiness. Happiness pills do not necessarily increase health and longevity—for that, you need health and longevity pills— and involuntary euthanasia would reduce longevity. So the NICE approach is not ‘utilitarian’, at least not in the classical Benthamite sense of maximising the sum total of all the happy experiences in the universe. The NICE approach is not crude, either. NICE is pluralistic about principles of justice and does not endorse the value judge- ment that sum total health impact is the only relevant ethical consideration. Cost-effectiveness is just one important consider- ation that NICE takes into account when reaching its decisions —not the only one. NICE does not set a rigid cost-effectiveness cut-off point for recommending healthcare technologies; it merely sets a cost-effectiveness range beyond which a positive recommendation requires particularly strong and careful justifi- cation through wider considerations. In line with the ‘account- ability for reasonableness’ framework described above, NICE formulates its recommendations through a deliberative process which involves diverse stakeholders and takes into account a wide range of considerations. NON-DISCRIMINATION The principle of non-discrimination acts as an ethical constraint on the principle of cost-effectiveness. Discussions about cost- effectiveness and discrimination in the medical ethics literature often focus on clinical decisions about particular individual patients. This is potentially misleading because in practice cost- effectiveness calculations based on QALYs are only ever used to inform population level decisions involving large numbers of unidentified patients. So here I want to consider a hypothetical example of potential disability discrimination that is more akin to the kinds of population level decisions made by NICE. Imagine NICE is faced with a new life extending treatment for stomach cancer that is borderline cost-effective in the full patient population. Further, imagine that the treatment has the same probability in all patents of a good biomedical response in terms of shrinking the tumour and restoring patients to their previous level of health and expected longevity. But now imagine it is not cost-effective for a subpopulation of severely disabled individuals, because their previous level of health and expected longevity are lower than average. The principle of cost-effectiveness thus suggests recommending that the treat- ment should be funded for most patients, but not for severely disabled patients. However, that would be an act of invidious discrimination against the disabled; it would generate political outrage; and it might also be contrary to European legislation on human rights. So NICE would not do it. Indeed, I doubt NICE advisory committees ever find themselves having to con- sider a cost-effectiveness argument for discriminating against the disabled, since subgroup analyses of cost-effectiveness based on severe disability are rarely if ever performed. NICE often under- takes subgroup analysis on suitable patient and treatment characteristics in pursuit of cost-effective ways of funding a par- ticular healthcare technology, but it does not strive officiously to find opportunities for disability discrimination. PRIORITY TO THE WORSE OFF Priority to the worse off in terms of severity of illness is a prin- ciple of justice that reflects policy concern to distribute health- care according to need, insofar as severity of illness is an important component of need. In pursuit of accountability, NICE has recently proposed two ways of measuring the severity or ‘burden’ of illness. First, the absolute shortfall from normal healthy life expectancy. This is the difference between the years of life in full health that the average person would expect, given their age and sex, and what the patient can expect given the severity of their disease. Second, the relative shortfall. This is the absolute shortfall expressed as a percentage of normal healthy life expectancy. Absolute shortfall tends to be larger in younger patients who have longer left to live and so will tend to suffer a larger absolute shortfall from any given disease in terms of years of healthy life lost. Importantly, NICE recognises that NHS patients who bear the health opportunity costs of its decisions may also be severely ill. So it compares severity of illness not against healthy indivi- duals with ‘zero’ severity of illness but against a benchmark severity of illness for the typical NHS patient. However, NICE has not gone so far as to specify a formula for giving greater weight to QALY gains for patients with more severe illnesses. This may be wise, given the complexity of judgements about justice and structural differences between principles of benefi- cence versus priority to the worse off.8 Instead, NICE will con- tinue to make these nuanced judgements on a case by case basis, through a deliberative process. A quite different way of defining the ‘worse off’ is in terms of lifetime health, rather than current severity of illness. Priority to the worse off in terms of lifetime health is a principle of justice that reflects policy concern to reduce social inequalities in lon- gevity and health.9 In a healthcare context, however, the prin- ciple of non-discrimination often acts as an ethical constraint against this principle. For example, the NHS might be able slightly to reduce social inequality in health by funding a treat- ment only for the poor. Yet this might seem like invidious dis- crimination against the rich. In my view, therefore, the principle of priority to those with poor lifetime health is typically more relevant in relation to healthcare decisions about improving access to and uptake of preventive healthcare, rather than deci- sions about whether to fund particular treatments. For example, this principle may be relevant in decisions about whether to locate smoking cessation clinics near affluent or deprived neigh- bourhoods, or whether to make special additional marketing and outreach efforts to encourage people from socially disad- vantaged backgrounds to attend a cancer screening programme. CONCLUSIONS I have argued that, when thinking about population level health- care decisions, opportunity costs for unidentified fellow citizens are an essential feature of the ethical landscape. Justice concerns Cookson R. J Med Ethics 2015;41:99–102. doi:10.1136/medethics-2014-102386 101 JME40: Good medical ethics o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://jm e .b m j.co m / J M e d E th ics: first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /m e d e th ics-2 0 1 4 -1 0 2 3 8 6 o n 1 6 D e ce m b e r 2 0 1 4 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://jme.bmj.com/ the distribution of burdens as well as benefits. So in order to take appropriate account of justice, good medical ethics requires careful consideration of the opportunity costs of healthcare decisions and who will bear them. We need to consider the total size of those opportunity costs in order to apply the ethical principle of beneficence or cost-effectiveness. We also need to consider who will bear those opportunity costs in order to apply the ethical principle of priority to the worse off. Funding RC is funded by a Senior Research Fellowship award from the National Institute for Health Research. Competing interests None. Disclaimer The views expressed in this publication are those of the author and not necessarily those of NICE, the NHS, the National Institute for Health Research or the Department of Health. Provenance and peer review Commissioned; internally peer reviewed. REFERENCES 1 Kahneman D. Thinking, fast and slow. 1st edn. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2011. 2 Greene JD. Moral tribes: emotion, reason, and the gap between us and them. Penguin Press, 2013. 3 Cozolino L. The neuroscience of human relationships: Attachment and the developing social brain. WW Norton & Company, 2014. 4 Daniels N. Accountability for reasonableness. BMJ 2000;321(7272):1300–1. 5 Shah KK, Cookson R, Culyer AJ, et al. NICE’s social value judgements about equity in health and health care. Health Econ Policy Law 2013;8(2):145–65. 6 Claxton K, Martin S, Soares M, et al. Methods for the estimation of the NICE cost effectiveness threshold. York: University of York, 2013. 7 Slovic P. If I look at the mass I will never act: Psychic numbing and genocide. Judgment Decis Mak 2007;2(2):79–95. 8 Broome J. Fairness versus doing the most good. Hastings Cent Rep 1994;24 (4):36–9. 9 Eyal N, Hurst SA, Norheim OF, et al. Inequalities in health: concepts, measures, and ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013. 102 Cookson R. J Med Ethics 2015;41:99–102. doi:10.1136/medethics-2014-102386 JME40: Good medical ethics o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://jm e .b m j.co m / J M e d E th ics: first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /m e d e th ics-2 0 1 4 -1 0 2 3 8 6 o n 1 6 D e ce m b e r 2 0 1 4 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://jme.bmj.com/ Justice and the NICE approach Abstract Introduction Cost-effectiveness Psychic numbing Crude utilitarianism? Non-discrimination Priority to the worse off Conclusions References work_ghkbrbpf5ngbrisjfydeyoac7y ---- pjn011 576..600 Chief Justice Roberts, Justice Alito, and New Federalism Jurisprudence Christopher Banks* andJohn Blakemany The Rehnquist Court returned power back to the states in rulings that scholars have dubbed ‘‘New Federalism.’’ The appointments of Chief Justice Roberts and Justice Alito invite speculation about the future direction of federalism cases in the Supreme Court. A survey of the Roberts Court’s federalism rulings discovers that the ideological pathways of new federalism depend upon Justice Kennedy’s swing vote and the effects the new appointments have on shaping voting coalitions in light of the vacancies they have filled. Although there is a reconfigured ‘‘States’ Rights Five’’ voting coalition, neither Roberts nor Alito endorses rigid viewpoints about federalism and it remains uncertain if the Court will return to the type of aggressive new federalism which arguably defined the legacy of the Rehnquist Court. It is reasonable to think the appointments of Chief Justice John G. Roberts, Jr and Associate Justice Samuel Alito would continue the progress toward new federalism jurisprudence1 in the ‘‘Roberts Court.’’ In spite of a series of rulings reaffirming federal regulation near the end of the Rehnquist Court (Nevada Department of Human Resources v. Hibbs [2003], Tennessee v. Lane [2004], Gonzales v. Raich [2005]), the Court’s sharp limits on Congress’s power to regulate state activities in U.S. v. Lopez (1995), City of Boerne v. Flores (1997), and U.S. v. Morrison (2000) are still very much intact. Although the Rehnquist Court’s singular impact in constraining the development of national public policy remains debatable (Clayton and Pickerill 2004), it is still renowned for its role in rearticulating states’ interests (Dinan 2004, 39). While early Roberts Court rulings demonstrated uneven support for states’ rights, the 2006–2007 term sheds more light on whether a conservative bloc will coalesce and aggressively protect the states in a manner reminiscent of the Rehnquist Court. In this light the change of personnel may also register another dynamic: Whether the justices purporting to favor the states are having trouble agreeing on basic anti-federalist principles, a tendency that increasingly typified later Rehnquist Court jurisprudence (Banks and Blakeman 2006). *Kent State University; E-mail: cbanks6@kent.edu yUniversity of Wisconsin-Stevens Point; E-mail: john.blakeman@uwsp.edu Publius:TheJournal of Federalism volume 38 number 3, pp.576^600 doi:10.1093/publius/pjn011 AdvanceAccess publication 24 April 2008 � TheAuthor 2008. Published by Oxford University Press on behalf of CSFAssociates: Publius, Inc. All rights reserved. For permissions, please email: journals.permissions@oxfordjournals.org. This essay surveys the Roberts Court’s federalism and highlights judicial conflicts on the bench and resulting from the new appointments. The cases denote that the ideological pathways of new federalism frequently depend upon Justice Anthony Kennedy’s swing vote, and that the new brethren are affecting precedents and internal coalitions in light of the vacancies they have filled. Chief Justice Roberts is a crucial replacement for Chief Justice Rehnquist, once described as the most important ‘‘judicial entrepreneur interested in pressing [the federalism] constitu- tional agenda’’ (Whittington 2001, 503), and who others hold responsible for igniting the ‘‘long fuse’’ for the state rights’ revival (Tushnet 2006, 255; see also Fry v. U.S.[1975]). Justice Sandra Day O’Connor’s absence is likewise critical because she was part of the five-justice coalition supporting states’ rights; and she or Justice Kennedy often provided the decisive fourth or fifth votes in limiting federal power (Claeys 2005, 792). Justice O’Connor’s minimalist judicial philosophy (Maveety 2003), along with her at times tepid support for the principles underlying new federalism (Tushnet 2003), are significant benchmarks to measure whether Justice Alito will follow her lead or, instead, drift further right and adapt the kind of rigorous orginalism defining Justice Clarence Thomas’s interest in protecting state sovereignty. Although they are part of a reconfigured ‘‘States’ Rights Five’’ voting bloc (Baker 2006, 205), the judicial record shows that neither Roberts nor Alito endorses rigid viewpoints about federalism. Thus, it is less predictable that the Court will return to the type of provocative new federalism jurisprudence epitomized by Lopez (1995) or Morrison (2000). After briefly touching upon Chief Justice Roberts’s and Justice Alito’s federalism viewpoints before joining the high court, key cases of the first two terms of the Roberts Court are analyzed, in order to detail their impact in solidifying the movement towards new federalism and the avid protection of state interests. The last section is an assessment of the impact of the new appointments in the Roberts Court. Pre-Supreme Court Federalism Positions The past judicial records, confirmation testimonies, and extra judicial writings of Chief Justice Roberts and Justice Alito reveal underlying patterns of judicial thought illustrating their approaches to federalism. At the core of each jurist’s thinking is the advocacy of judicial restraint as a means to advance structural limitations on federal power in a ‘‘dual sovereignty’’ constitutional framework. In a National Public Radio interview with Nina Totenberg on June 24, 1999, Judge Roberts defined federalism in structural terms by describing rulings invigorating states’ interests as ‘‘a healthy reminder that we’re a country that was formed by States and that we still live under a Federal system . . . The cases remind us that New Federalism Jurisprudence 577 ‘‘the States, as co-equal sovereigns, have their own sovereign powers, and that includes, as everyone at the time of the Constitutional Convention understood, sovereign immunity’’ (Committee on the Judiciary, U.S. Senate 2003b, 267). Similarly, for Alito judges ‘‘should be careful not to usurp the rightful powers of the other branches of the federal government or those of the states and their subdivisions,’’ because one of the most important safeguards of freedom is ‘‘the separation and distribution of government powers’’ (Committee on the Judiciary, U.S. Senate 1990, 650). At their confirmation hearings the chief justice and Justice Alito addressed the scope of congressional commerce regulation, but each expressed different levels of support for it. Although liberal critics argued that Roberts’s D.C. Circuit dissent in Rancho Viejo LLC v. Norton, (2003) reflected a narrow conception of commerce authority in environment cases (Fortenberry and Beck 2005, 76, 81–84), other evidence showed a healthy respect for limiting state sovereignty. In discussing Gonzales v. Raich (2005), he acknowledged the nearly conclusive weight of New Deal precedents under the commerce clause; but he also declared that U.S. v. Lopez (1995) and U.S. v. Morrison (2000) ‘‘did not junk all the cases that came before’’ (Lazarus 2006, 15). In contrast, when asked about Raich at his own hearings, Judge Alito interpreted Lopez differently by implying that it did not necessarily preserve the Court’s post-New Deal commerce clause precedents, perhaps because of his dissent as a Third Circuit judge in U.S. v. Rybar [1996] (Lazarus 2006, 29). In Rybar, Judge Alito dissented from the ruling that Congress could regulate intrastate possession of machine guns under the commerce clause. In disagreeing, Alito dismissed his colleagues’ ringing endorsement of federal power over intrastate conduct because it reduced the Lopez precedent to being ‘‘a constitutional freak’’ (Rybar 1996, 287). Essential to Roberts’s and Alitos’ commerce clause analysis is the sufficiency of congressional findings, a judicial tendency that also colors their views of Section Five (of the Fourteenth Amendment), conditional spending, and sovereignty immunity cases. As a nominee, Judge Roberts accepted few constraints on congressional commerce power so long as there is proof that the activity under review is adequately connected to interstate commerce (Committee on the Judiciary, U.S. Senate 2005, 226, 260–264, 440; Fortenberry and Beck 2005, 80–84). As Roberts explained, if judges get to the ‘‘point of reweighing congressional findings, that starts to look more like a legislative function,’’ and courts must ‘‘make sure that they’re interpreting the law and not making it’’ (Committee on the Judiciary, U.S. Senate 2005, 219). Similarly, not only did Alito testify that the judiciary must have ‘‘great respect’’ for congressional fact-finding, he also went so far as to admit that he probably would not have dissented in Rybar, if Congress had compiled findings linking the intrastate possession of machine guns 578 C. Banks and J. Blakeman to interstate commerce (Committee on the Judiciary, U.S. Senate 2006, 389). Although Judge Alito conceded that the machine gun statute might have withstood constitutional scrutiny, he further explained that: . . . neither Congress, the Executive (in the form of government lawyers who briefed and argued the case), nor the majority has adduced any appreciable empirical proof . . . . I would view this case differently if Congress as a whole or even one of the responsible congressional committees had made a finding that intrastate machinegun possession . . . has a substantial effect on interstate commerce. But despite the resources at their command to investigate questions such as this, neither Congress nor any of its committees did so . . . [and] congressional findings would enable us to evaluate the legislative judgment that the activity in question substantially affected interstate commerce . . . [but] they are lacking here (Rybar [1996], 293, quoting U.S. v. Lopez [1995]). Such commentary reveals that each justice gives great weight to empirical proof; but doing so can cut both ways and either advance or hinder state interests. Whereas heightened scrutiny of congressional fact-finding arguably protects individual rights in the states by imposing limits on legislative influence, it also may become the basis for trumping state claims to Eleventh Amendment sovereignty immunity or, alternatively, increasing federal enforcement against individual rights based on Section Five of the Fourteenth Amendment. In legal terms, if Congress expresses a clear and unequivocal intent to waive state immunity or, in Section Five cases, Congress can establish a congruence and proportionality between the exercise of federal power and the target of the regulation, the testimonies inferred that each jurist is likely to give preference to federal prerogatives. The affinity to look for empirical facts is illustrated by Judge Roberts’s confirmation discussion of Section Five abrogation of state immunity in cases alleging discrimination under the federal American with Disabilities Act, an issue in Board of Trustees of the University of Alabama v. Garrett (2001) and Tennessee v. Lane (2004). In Garrett, the Court insulated Alabama from a federal lawsuit by a discharged state employee and cancer victim alleging discrimination under the ADA’s Title I. In Lane, federal power was extended to let a paraplegic plaintiff who was denied physical access to a court sue Tennessee under the public accom- modations provision, or ADA’s Title II. In spite of the different outcomes, Roberts asserted that in both cases the Court did not substitute its policy judgment for that of Congress. Instead, it engaged in principled decision-making by focusing on whether Congress established unequivocal factual findings that state governments transgressed federal disability law and which therefore justified a waiver of state sovereign immunity (Committee on the Judiciary, U.S. Senate 2005, 420–421). New Federalism Jurisprudence 579 Thus, for Roberts, Congress may remedy anti-discrimination practices in the states under Section Five in appropriate factual circumstances. In like fashion, Judge Alito’s Third Circuit record demonstrated that the judicial line between congressional power and state immunity was drawn on the sufficiency of empirical facts. In Chittister v. Pennsylvania Department of Community and Economic Development (2000), a case involving Congress’ abrogation of Eleventh Amendment immunity under the Family Medical Leave Act (FMLA), Judge Alito looked to the Supreme Court’s precedents in Kimel v. Florida Board of Regents (2000) and City of Boerne v. Flores (1997) to strike down the FMLA on the grounds that there were no congressional findings about the prevalence of gender discrimination in medical leave policies; hence the law was incongruent and disproportionate as a remedy of state violations (Chittister 2000, 228–229). Notably, Chittister did not apply the Kimel standard, under which congressional waivers of state immunity must be unmistakably clear in the statute’s language; but the federal law failed Boerne’s congruence and proportionality test, and Judge Alito’s opinion relied heavily on the lack of legislative findings to discount Congress’s reasons for waiving state immunity. As a result, Alito’s opinion approximates his Rybar dissent because both depend a great deal on the absence of empirical proof to validate federal regulation. Before their appointments, each judge accepted Congress’s authority under the spending clause to compel states to waive their Eleventh Amendment immunity if they receive federal monies, provided there is a clear nexus between the federal law’s purpose and state spending. Roberts and Alito supported Congress’s spending power under South Dakota v. Dole (1987) to require states to fulfill conditions before they receive federal monies if it is built upon a firm foundation of congressional fact-finding (Committee on the Judiciary, U.S. Senate 2003b, 267). As a D.C. Circuit judge, Roberts endorsed Barbour v. Washington Metropolitan Area Transit Authority (2004), which held that a State entity could be sued in federal court because Congress statutorily declared its intent to condition the receipt of federal monies upon a waiver of state immunity. Although Alito’s views of congressional spending power were not detailed in any cases or during his confirmation hearings, he acknowledged Dole’s precedential value as giving Congress ‘‘very broad authority’’ over federal spending. Congress could, therefore, ‘‘attach all sorts of conditions to receipt of federal aid,’’ provided they are clear and relevant to the purposes of funding (Committee on the Judiciary, U.S. Senate 2006, 621). Also, a different Third Circuit ruling, New Jersey Payphone Association v. Town of West New York (2002), provides hints as to Judge Alito’s views on federal preemption. At issue was whether a municipality’s grant of an exclusive pay phone franchise on public rights of way is preempted by the 1996 Telecommunications Act. Although the court held the local ordinance was preempted, Judge Alito declined to 580 C. Banks and J. Blakeman reach the preemption question by reasoning it was unnecessary to do so. As he explained: The rationales behind the doctrine of avoiding constitutional questions except as a last resort are grounded in fundamental constitutional principles—the ‘great gravity and delicacy’ of judicial review . . . and principles of federalism . . . Moreover, the federalism rationale is pertinent here because we have the option of avoiding invocation of federal supremacy over local laws. Therefore, resolving this case on state-law grounds does less violence to principles of federalism and dual sovereignty (New Jersey Payphone Association 2002, 249–50). Thus, Judge Alito viewed preemption prudentially, and perhaps as a last resort when overarching federalism principles are at stake. Whereas some of Alito’s views on preemption were disclosed, Roberts’s position is hard to discern. Yet, some of his off-the-bench writings have federalism overtones that are sensitive to states’ rights, and they infer he respects justiciability requirements. Of the eleven publications Judge Roberts listed in the Senate Judi- ciary Committee Questionnaire (Committee on the Judiciary, U.S. Senate 2005, 64), two law reviews speak to the protection of individual property rights in the states in the ‘‘takings’’ and ‘‘contract clause’’ context: He advocates against strict judicial construction of constitutional text because it would diminish those rights (Roberts 1978a, 1978b). In a Wall Street Journal article, Roberts analyzed President Clinton’s appointment of Drew Days as Solicitor General and suggested that the transfer of power from Solicitor Ken Starr may lead to fewer amicus brief filings that would otherwise protect over-burdened state governments from effectively fighting street crime, preventing abortion, and stopping affirmative action (Roberts 1993a). Also, Roberts defended the Supreme Court’s strict interpretation of the standing doctrine by ‘‘recognizing that Article III [and its ‘case and controversy’ requirement] is a constraint on Congress’s power to assign matters to the federal courts’’ (Roberts 1993b, 1229). The pre-Supreme Court portraits of each jurist, moreover, may address ideological differences that they have with the justices they are replacing and with whom they are serving on the bench. For instance, Roberts has publicly distanced himself from endorsing an original or strict understanding of constitutional text (Committee on the Judiciary, U.S. Senate 2005, 298–299; Committee on the Judiciary, U.S. Senate 2003a, 57); if true, that sets him apart from Justices Scalia or Thomas. Similarly, but only if one overlooks the anti-nationalist position he took in Rybar in light of Lopez, Judge Alito’s later acknowledgement of Congress’s broad and evolutionary commerce power at his Supreme Court confirmation hearing (Committee on the Judiciary, U.S. Senate 2006, 628) tends to set him apart New Federalism Jurisprudence 581 from Justice Thomas’s originalist reading of the interstate commerce clause (which makes a distinction between commerce and other forms of economic activity). Also, whereas Justice Alito’s posture on the scope of Congress’s spending authority is less clear, Chief Justice Roberts’s inclination to defer to Congress in federal conditional spending cases may distinguish him from Justice Sandra Day O’Connor, who dissented in Dole (1987). Finally, on the question of whether the national political process can effectively safeguard the states’ interests in structural terms, it is noteworthy that Justice Alito implied in Rybar that normative limits on federal power exist outside of the political process. As a result, Justice Alito arguably does not agree with the ‘‘political safeguards’’ argument and, accordingly, he offers continuity with Justice O’Connor’s federalism jurisprudence in respect to the political safeguards approach (see Justice O’Connor’s dissents in Raich [2005], or Garcia v. San Antonio Metropolitan Transit Authority [1985]; Huhn 2006). Federalism in the Roberts Court The vagaries of Chief Justice Roberts’s and Justice Alito’s pre-Supreme Court federalism views accentuate their potential in significantly affecting the doctrinal and ideological pathways of the Roberts Court’s emerging new federalism jurisprudence. While the first two terms offer insight into the trend of several commerce clause, spending clause, and sovereign immunity cases, Massachusetts v. Environmental Protection Agency (2007) and Watters v. Wachovia Bank (2007) may be the most significant statements of the role that justiciability and preemption doctrines will play in delimiting federal power and state sovereignty. While Gonzales v. Carhart (2007) probably remains the Court’s most important political decision regulating abortion, it also had a federalism dimension because it conspicuously left unanswered whether Congress can regulate abortions in the states under the commerce clause. After briefly discussing the Massachusetts and Watters rulings, the federalism implications of Carhart are addressed. Thereafter, the inroads made by the justices in the remaining areas of federalism doctrine are synthesized. Table 1 provides a summary of significant Roberts Court federalism decisions and voting alignments. In the 5:4 ruling of Massachusetts (2007), the Court’s liberal wing, plus Justice Kennedy, granted Massachusetts standing to contest the EPA’s decision not to regulate the emission of greenhouse gases from new cars and possibly ease the problem of global warming. Justice John Paul Steven’s majority opinion reasoned that the Clean Air Act vested in Massachusetts a procedural right to challenge agency nonaction on behalf of its citizens. Chief Justice Roberts’s dissent, joined by Justices Scalia, Thomas, and Alito, countered that the case was a nonjusticiable ‘‘case or controversy’’ under Article III. Because Massachusetts did not establish a link between its harm and the agency’s failure to act, Chief Justice Roberts flatly 582 C. Banks and J. Blakeman Table 1 Roberts Court Federalism Decisions (2006–2007) Case Federalism issue Federalism implications Voting alignments U.S. v. Georgia 126 S. Ct. 877 (2006) 11th A. Sovereign Immunity; Sec. 5 of 14th A. Enforcement (not decided) Title II of American Disabilities Act abrogates state sovereign immunity 9:0 Sc, St, OC, RBG, So, K, Br, Th, Ro g Con: St, RBG Gonzales v. Oregon 546 U.S. 243 (2006) Commerce Clause U.S. Attorney General could not enforce Controlled Substances Act against physicians applying state assisted suicide law under commerce authority 6:3 K, St, OC, So, RBG, Br g Diss: Sc, Th, Ro g Diss: Th Central Va. Comm. College v. Katz 546 U.S. 356 (2006) 11th A. Sovereign Immunity Art. I Bankruptcy Clause abrogates state sovereign immunity 5:4 St, OC, RBG, So, Br g Diss: Th, Sc, K, Ro Northern Ins. Co. v. Chatham 547 U.S. 189 (2006) 11th A. and Common Law Sovereign Immunity State county could not claim 11th A. and Common Law Sovereign Immunity 9:0 Th, St, Sc, RBG, So, K, Br, Ro, Al Rapanos v. U.S. Army Corps of Engineers 126 S. Ct. 2208 (2006) Commerce Clause Congress could not regulate wetlands on private land as navigable waters in interstate commerce under Clean Water Act 4:1:4 Sc, Th, Ro, Al g Con (in result): K g Diss: St, RBG, So, Br Arlington Central School Dist Bd. v. Murphy 126 S. Ct. 2455 (2006) Spending Clause Federal Individuals with Disabilities Education Act did not allow recovery of expert fees by parents in legal action against school boards under Article I Spending Clause 6:3 Al, Sc, K, Th, Ro g Con/Diss (in part, in result): RBG g Diss: So g Diss: Br, St, So Massachusetts v. EPA 127 S. Ct. 1438 (2007) Standing of states asserting Quasi-Sovereign Interests States asserting quasi-sovereign interests in protecting citizens against ill-effects of global warming have standing to sue EPA for its decision not to regulate greenhouse gas emissions of new cars 5:4 St, K, So, RBG, Br g Diss: Ro, Sc, Th, Al continued N ew F ed eralism Ju risp ru d en ce 5 8 3 Table 1 Continued Case Federalism issue Federalism implications Voting alignments Watters v. Wachovia Bank 127 S. Ct. 1559 (2007) Preemption; 10th A.; Commerce Power Federal National Bank Act preempts state mortgage lending laws pertaining to sub- sidiary of federally-licensed banking institu- tion; and national banking regulation is within commerce authority and not barred by the Tenth Amendment 5:3 RBG, K, So, Br, Al g Diss: St, Sc, Ro g Th did not participate United Haulers Ass’n v. Oneida-Herkimer Solid Waste Mangmt. Auth. 127 S. Ct. 1786 (2007) Dormant Commerce Clause County ordinance does not violate dormant commerce clause by requiring private haul- ers to use local publicly-owned waste facilities 6:3 Ro, Sc, So, Th, RBG, Br g Con (in part): Sc g Con (in result): Th g Diss: Al, St, K Winkelman v. Parma City School Dist. 127 S. Ct. 1994 (2007) Spending Clause Federal Individuals with Disabilities Education Act permits parents to proceed pro se in legal action against state school boards, independent of Congress’s Article I Spending Clause 7:2 K, St, So, RBG, Br, Ro, A g Diss/Con (in part): Sc, Th Note: Opinions for the Court, plurality opinions, concurring, and dissenting opinions are abbreviated, with its author identified in bold, are listed in far right column. Key: Chief Justice John Roberts (Ro); Justice John Paul Stevens (St); Justice Antonin Scalia (Sc); Justice Anthony Kennedy (K); Justice David Souter (So); Justice Clarence Thomas (Th); Justice Stephen Breyer (Br); Justice Samuel Alito (Al); Justice Ruth Bader Ginsburg (RBG); Justice Sandra Day O’Connor (OC). Source: Supreme Court of the U.S. homepage, at http://www.supremecourtus.gov (accessed October 9, 2007). 5 8 4 C . B an k s an d J. B lak em an http:// denied that states are entitled to a ‘‘special solicitude’’ in standing analysis simply because they assert a quasi-sovereign interest in protecting citizens against the specter of catastrophic rising sea levels. If anything, Roberts concluded, a State making that type of claim must satisfy a higher threshold of standing under the Court’s precedents, which require that citizens, as well as the State itself, suffer direct harm. In short, under federal law the states do not enjoy any ‘‘special rights or status’’ to request, as aggrieved litigants, judicial relief from the Environmental Protection Agency’s political decision to not regulate greenhouse gases (Massachusetts 2007, 1464). Although Justice Alito’s Third Circuit New Jersey Payphone opinion may have inferred a lukewarm endorsement of the preemption doctrine, he joined most of the Court’s liberal wing (plus Justice Kennedy) to hold in Watters v. Wachovia Bank (2007) that a subsidiary of a federally chartered bank did not have to comply with registration and auditing requirements that were a part of state, but not federal, mortgage lending laws. In contrast to Justice Ruth Bader Ginsburg’s majority opinion declaring that the lending activities of federal subsidiaries were controlled by the National Banking Act, Chief Justice Roberts and Justice Scalia joined with Justice Stevens in dissent2 to argue that nondiscriminatory state regu- lations, which do not impede federal law are immune from federal control. In that Congress did not express a ‘‘clear and manifest purpose’’ in its laws to regulate federally licensed affiliates, the dissent maintained the Court’s ruling showed less than ‘‘a healthy respect for state sovereignty’’ (Watters 2007, 1584) and diminished the ‘‘vital role state legislation plays in the dual banking system’’ (Watters 2007, 1574). Notably, in dicta, Chief Justice Roberts and Justice Scalia conceded the majority’s point that the Tenth Amendment did not constrain federal power as exercised under the commerce and elastic clauses; still, they took special note of it because it was ‘‘included in the Bill of Rights, [and that] should . . . remind the Court that its ruling affects the allocation of powers among sovereigns . . . [and] the reasons for adopting that Amendment are precisely those that undergird the well-established presumption against preemption’’ (Watters 2007 1585). Prior to Gonzales v. Carhart (2007), which upheld, 5:4, the federal Partial-Birth Abortion Ban Act, court watchers speculated about whether the justices would answer if Congress’s commerce power extended to regulating abortions in the states (Devins 2007; Pushaw 2005). At first blush, the case squarely presented the issue because the ban was explicitly based on the commerce clause and, under Gonzales v. Raich (2005), the Court implied that Congress had sweeping power to regulate activities with an economic dimension if there was a rational basis to do so. Also, the commerce issue seemed ripe for resolution for other reasons. Anti-abortion critics typically argue that abortion regulation is a province of the states. A bevy of new federalism rulings, among them U.S. v. Lopez (1995) and U. S. v. Morrison (2000), and arguably Gonzales v. Oregon (2006), and Rapanos v. U.S. Army Corps of Engineers (2006) (but decided principally on statutory grounds, and discussed shortly), New Federalism Jurisprudence 585 appeared to limit commerce authority. Also, at least three justices, Justices Scalia, Thomas, and Alito, have gone on record opposing Roe v. Wade (1973). In spite of its legal ambiguity and political ramifications, the prospect of commerce clause regulation was only briefly raised at oral argument, and the legal issue was not briefed. Accordingly, Justice Kennedy’s plurality opinion did not address it, presumably on prudential grounds. Even so, that did not stop Justice Thomas from specially observing in a brief concurrence joined by Justice Scalia that the commerce clause issue was not addressed in the briefs, a sign that those justices may want to revisit the issue but that the Chief Justice and Justice Alito might not. Commerce Clause Interpretations The Roberts Court made additional, and at times more definitive, statements about commerce clause federalism in Gonzales v. Oregon (2006), Rapanos v. U.S. Army Corps of Engineers (2006), and United Haulers Association v. Oneida-Herkimer Solid Waste Management Authority (2007). Without Justice Alito on the bench, in Gonzales v. Oregon (2006) Justices Anthony Kennedy and Sandra Day O’Connor joined the liberal bloc in a 6:3 decision to strike down the U.S. Attorney General’s authority under the federal Controlled Substances Act (CSA) to prevent state doctors from using drugs that assisted in patient suicide under Oregon’s Death with Dignity Act. The outcome was reached via statutory interpretation and purported to favor the states. Yet, all the justices agreed that Congress possessed commerce authority to prevent state-assisted suicide. Chief Justice Roberts, along with Justice Thomas, joined Scalia’s dissent arguing the Attorney General acted within the bounds of the statute to regulate death-producing drugs; but only Justice Thomas, in a separate dissent, questioned the inconsistency of not allowing the CSA to be used to prevent intrastate suicides in Oregon, while permitting it to stop the intrastate use of medicinal marijuana in California under Raich. In his words, ‘‘The Court’s reliance upon the constitutional principles that it rejected in Raich— albeit under the guise of statutory interpretation—is perplexing to say the least’’ (Gonzales 2006, 302). With Justice Alito confirmed and on the bench, in Rapanos v. U.S. Army Corps of Engineers (2006) the Court fractured into three groups (4:1:4) in deciding whether the U.S. Army Corps of Engineers could assert jurisdiction over state wetlands under the Clean Water Act on the grounds that ditches or man-made drains emptied into federally controlled navigable waters. Contrary to the liberal bloc’s preferences, Justice Scalia, plus Chief Justice Roberts, and Justices Thomas and Alito, denied federal jurisdiction. Justice Kennedy cast the deciding vote, but in a stand-alone concurrence did not fully embrace Scalia’s plurality rationale or the dissent’s deferential position, led by John Paul Stevens, and joined by Justices Souter, Ginsburg, and Breyer. What remained was a narrow construction of the 586 C. Banks and J. Blakeman CWA and a jurisdictional rule requiring a ‘‘significant nexus’’ between the wetlands at issue and navigable waters (Adler 2006). The fragmented outcome produced a remand, and probably created little guidance for understanding the true limits of federalism in analogous water cases; although some maintain that Justice Kennedy’s test in significant in striking a pragmatic balance between federal and state interests (Harvard Law Review Association 2006, 358). New insights—as well as additional disagreement across and between the political spectrums—came from the Court’s analysis of the so-called negative, or dormant, commerce clause in United Haulers Association v. Oneida-Herkimer Solid Waste Management Authority (2007). There, in a 6:3 ruling by Chief Justice Roberts, federal commerce power did not void a county flow-control ordinance requiring private haulers to use local publicly owned waste facilities that charged higher ‘‘tipping’’ fees as compared to those found out-of-state. An unusual cohort of justices in the majority, namely the Chief Justice, Souter, Ginsburg, Breyer, Thomas, and Scalia, reasoned the ordinance did not discriminate against interstate commerce even though it favored local government at the expense of the private trash industry. The public interest in allowing the county flow ordinance to stand, the Court said, outweighed the interest private haulers had in minimizing their costs. For Roberts, not making a distinction between the public and private interests at stake encouraged judicial activism of the worse sort, giving the judiciary a ‘‘roving license’’ to create policies about waste regulation that ought to be decided by the democratic processes (United Haulers 2007, 1796). Yet, in separate concurrences Justice Scalia and Thomas questioned the Court’s reliance on precedents supporting the negating effect of the commerce clause on state laws and the underlying politics producing them. Whereas Scalia called it ‘‘an unjustified judicial intervention’’ (United Haulers 2007, 1798), Thomas went further by saying he would ‘‘discard’’ it altogether as an ‘‘unworkable’’ set of guidelines unjustifiably permitting the Court to usurp economic policymaking of either Congress or state governments in regulating trash disposal (United Haulers 2007, 1799). In a dissent joined by Justices Stevens and Kennedy, Justice Alito accepted the Court’s role in developing its dormant commerce clause jurisprudence but argued that the precedents themselves did not justify ‘‘an exception for discrimination in favor of a state-owned entity’’ (United Haulers 2007, 1806). That is, the distinction the Court used to favor state interests amounted to a discriminatory form of economic protectionism that runs counter to the ‘‘usual dormant Commerce Clause standards’’ prohibiting different treatment (United Haulers 2007, 1809). Although the shifting coalitions among the justices in commerce clause cases make it difficult to pin down their ideological preferences, some patterns nonetheless emerge. The dichotomous results in Oregon and Rapanos, with each going in contrary directions in accepting federal regulation over assisted suicides New Federalism Jurisprudence 587 and wetlands, are reconcilable as decisions based on statutory interpretation. In spite of the different outcomes, Chief Justice Roberts was aligned with Justices Scalia and Thomas in both cases, and Justice Alito joined that bloc in limiting federal power in Rapanos after he was confirmed. Still, the positions and signals expressed by Scalia and Thomas in all of the cases may set them apart from Roberts and Alito, for political and doctrinal reasons: (i) whereas in Carhart Scalia and Thomas hinted they might object to allowing Congress to use commerce authority to outlaw abortions, the Chief Justice and Alito chose not to speak on the issue; (ii) in Rapanos, all the justices except for Scalia and Thomas voiced support for the constitutional use of commerce power; and (iii) in United Haulers, only Scalia and Thomas questioned the underlying dormant commerce clause precedents. Spending Clause Interpretations The Individuals with Disabilities Education Act (IDEA) is legislation enacted under Congress’s spending (and Section Five of Fourteenth Amendment) authority that conditions the receipt of federal dollars for states adopting federal guidelines, which control educational intervention and related services for children with special needs. Two cases, Arlington Central School District Board v. Murphy (2006) and Winkelman v. Parma City School District (2007), identified the limits of federalism by addressing, in Arlington Central, the recovery of expert fees by parents who prevailed in a civil suit against a school board; whereas, in Winkelman, the dispute concerned if parents, acting independently apart from their children’s interests, could file an IDEA lawsuit without legal counsel. Justice Alito, writing on behalf of the Chief Justice and Justices Scalia, Kennedy, and Thomas, used Arlington Central to extract from a prior Spending Clause case, Pennhurst State School and Hospital v. Halderman (1981), a requirement that Congress must express ‘‘clear notice’’ that it intended to bind the States to the reimbursement of expert fees in setting conditions for the receipt of federal monies (Arlington Central 2006, 2459). That intent, he emphasized, was not ‘‘what a majority of the Members of both Houses intend,’’ but rather consists of the states being ‘‘clearly told’’ about the ‘‘conditions that go along with the acceptance of those funds’’ (Arlington Central 2006, 2463). In contrast, Justices Ginsburg (in a separate concurrence in the result only) united with dissenting Justices Souter, Breyer, and Stevens in contesting the creation of a new limitation on Congress’s spending power based on a clear intent rule (Arlington Central 2006, 2464, 2470). Yet, in Winkelman (2007), all the justices except two agreed with Justice Kennedy’s opinion holding that the ‘‘entire statutory scheme’’ underlying IDEA gave parents independent and enforceable rights relative to their children’s education, including the option to sue pro se (Winkelman 2007, 2000). In doing so, the Court distinguished Arlington Central and rejected the school district’s 588 C. Banks and J. Blakeman argument that Congress, under the Spending Clause, failed to give clear notice that states could be sued by parents seeking to vindicate their own child’s rights, even though ‘‘some rights repose in both the parent and the child’’ (Winkelman 2007, 2006). Justice Scalia, in a partial concurrence and dissent joined by Justice Thomas, did not address the Spending Clause argument; but they did write separately to state IDEA should not be interpreted to construct a general substantive parental right to education. Instead, for Scalia and Thomas it only let the parents proceed pro se in regards to asking for reimbursement of monies incurred in sending their kids to private school or to correct violations of their own procedural rights (Winkelman 2007, 2007). In evaluating the judicial lines drawn in the two spending cases, it remains unclear whether the decision by Chief Justice Roberts and Justice Alito to align themselves with a contextual reading of IDEA in Winkelman also implies that the law, for them, carries the type of substantive connotation that the dissent rejected. Still, it may underscore two closely related points. It may be further evidence that like-minded conservative justices fundamentally disagree on issues of statutory construction, with Justices Kennedy, Roberts, and Alito accepting what most would consider a liberal view based on statutory context and purpose. Also, Justice Scalia and Thomas’s Winkelman dissent did not address the spending clause issue—which perhaps may foreshadow they sponsor limits on Congress’s spending authority in future cases because they did not join with the rest of the Court in distinguishing the legal application of Arlington Central’s clear notice rule in Winkelman. State Sovereign Immunity Interpretations In U.S. v. Georgia (2006), a unanimous Court (without Justice Alito) construed Congress’s Fourteenth Amendment Section Five power to permit the federal American with Disabilities Act to allow a paraplegic prisoner to sue a state prison for actual unconstitutional violations pertaining to his confinement. That enforcement power, Justice Scalia’s majority opinion held, additionally abrogates state sovereign immunity under the Eleventh Amendment. In second case, predating Justice Alito’s confirmation, state immunity was likewise upheld to be validly abolished by Congress in a federal bankruptcy proceeding by a 5:4 ruling in Central Virginia Community College v. Katz (2006). The justices divided bitterly over their readings of whether the history of bankruptcy clause vested in Congress the ability to subordinate state sovereignty in the interest of securing uniformity in debtor–creditor relations among the states. Justice Stevens’ opinion, consisting of a bare majority of Justices O’Connor, Souter, Ginsburg, and Breyer, thought that it did, whereas the dissent, led by Justice Thomas and joined by Chief Justice Roberts, Scalia, and Kennedy, declared that it did not, adding that the result cannot ‘‘be justified by the text, structure, or history of our Constitution’’ (Central Virginia New Federalism Jurisprudence 589 Community College 2006, 379). The judicial conflict over the proper scope of state immunity eased with Northern Insurance Co. v. Chatham County (2006), a unanimous opinion by Justice Thomas (including Justice Alito) that held a county being sued for negligently operating a drawbridge could not assert sovereignty immunity because it was not ‘‘an arm of the state’’ when it controlled the bridge. Georgia invariably complicates the judicial lines drawn in the series of earlier Section Five rulings that at first cut back (U.S. v. Morrison [2000], Kimel v. Florida Board of Regents [2000], Board of Trustees of University of Alabama v. Garrett [2001]), but then expanded federal power in later opinions construing the scope of federal disabilities law (Nevada Department of Human Resources v. Hibbs [2003], Tennessee v. Lane [2004]). Yet, the Court’s holding may best be viewed as confined to its facts and only pertaining to actually established constitutional violations under the Fourteenth Amendment. Even with Justice Alito participating, Chatham’s effect is probably similar because the Court’s precedents barring entities that are not deemed part of state operations consistently ban claims of immunity. In light of Justice O’Connor’s departure, the more interesting ambiguity concerns the effect Justice Alito will have in subsequent litigation testing the scope and limits of Central Virginia in federal bankruptcy or analogous economic regulation, especially in the context of claims made by states to sovereign immunity. The Court’s 2007^2008 Term and Beyond Early in the 2007–2008 term, the Roberts Court decided a federalism case involving the limits of state taxation policy, plus it ruled on three other preemption cases and it resolved a rather unique appeal relating to the confluence of presidential power, international law, and state criminal justice administration. It was also scheduled to settle at least one additional dormant commerce clause case (as applied to state taxation). The cases not only help clarify the judicial lines between the justices, they also accentuate the impact of the Chief Justice and Justice Alito on new federalism jurisprudence. What the cases will not ostensibly reveal, however, is another dynamic interposed by Justice Thomas and his interpretation of the First Amendment’s Establishment Clause in religion cases with federalism dimensions. In that some states have used Justice Thomas’s interpretation in litigation, his argument and its constitutional implications are briefly outlined following a discussion of the preemption, state taxation, and international law cases. In Riegel v. Medtronic, Inc. (2008), the Court applied preemption to prohibit state common law claims challenging the safety or effectiveness of preapproved FDA medical devices. At issue was whether an injured heart patient could sue a catheter manufacturer under state tort law when the device failed in an operation in light of a federal law barring such claims. The Court, in an 8:1 ruling delivered over Justice Ginsburg’s dissent, held that the federal Medical Device Amendments (MDA) 590 C. Banks and J. Blakeman of 1976 preempts state common law claims against the manufacturers of FDA- approved medical devices. Writing for the Court, Justice Scalia reasoned that Congress clearly meant to preempt all state regulations that interfered with federal safety oversight of medical devices; but ‘‘only to the extent’’ that they are dissimilar to federal law (Riegel 2008, 1011). Thus, the MDA allows state common law claims ‘‘premised on a violation of FDA regulations; the state duties in such a case ‘parallel’ . . . the federal requirement’’ (Riegel 2008, 1011). In dissent Justice Ginsburg disagreed, and she refused to read the MDA ‘‘as an automatic bar to state common law tort claims’’ (Riegel 2008, 1019). In her view, ‘‘the purpose of Congress is the ultimate touchstone of pre-emption analysis’’ and hence the ‘‘constriction of state authority . . . was not mandated by Congress and is at odds with the MDA’s central purpose: to protect consumer safety’’ (Riegel 2008, 1013, 1020). As a result, Congress did not intend ‘‘to effect a radical curtailment of state common law suits’’ (Riegel 2008, 1013). Notably, in a partial dissent and concurrence, Justice Stevens joined the majority’s conclusion that the text of federal law barred state-based tort claims when state requirements were different; but he agreed with Justice Ginsburg that Congress could not have silently foreclosed all judicial recourse for consumers hurt by FDA-approved devises, a position that the majority embraced in the part of the opinion that Justice Stevens refused to join. In Rowe v. New Hampshire Motor Transport Association (2008), the State of Maine required licensed retailers that ship tobacco products to use a delivery service that verified recipients were of legal age to purchase tobacco. With Justices Ginsburg and Scalia filing separate concurrences, the Court held unanimously that the Federal Aviation Administration Authorization Act of 1994 (which regu- lates trucking companies, among other things) preempted Maine’s regulation. By interpreting precedent, which allowed for the preemption of state consumer- protection laws, Justice Breyer’s Opinion for the Court held Maine’s law interfered with Congress’ intent to deregulate the trucking industry and to favor free market competition. As well, the Court was unwilling to adopt, as per Maine’s argument, a public health exception that would allow a state to regulate tobacco deliveries as a step to protect public health. In construing congressional intent, the justices declared that the legislature clearly meant to further a national policy of deregulation; and Congress did not want to create ‘‘an implicit general ‘public health’ exception broad enough’’ to cover the delivery of tobacco that Maine sought to regulate (Rowe 2008, 997). As in Riegel, moreover, Justice Ginsburg’s separate concurrence understood that preemption’s application sometimes leads to harsh results. While she agreed with the Court, she wrote apart to express her doubt that Congress intended an outcome harming minors when it deregulated the trucking industry; and to signal Congress that it ought to ‘‘fill that gap’’ in national policy by creating legislation that would account for state laws designed to restrict minors’ access to tobacco (Rowe 2008, 998). New Federalism Jurisprudence 591 In a third preemption case, Preston v. Ferrer (2008), Justice Ginsburg joined her colleagues in deciding whether the Federal Arbitration Act (FAA) preempts state laws, which refer state law contract disputes to administrative agencies. The Court, with only Justice Thomas dissenting, ruled that ‘‘when parties agree to arbitrate all questions arising under a contract, state laws lodging primary jurisdiction in another forum, whether judicial or administrative, are superseded by the FAA’’ (Preston 2008, 981). Writing for the Court, Justice Ginsburg observed that the FAA established a ‘‘national policy favoring arbitration of claims that parties contract to settle in that manner,’’ and it ‘‘forecloses state legislative attempts to undercut the enforceability of arbitration agreements’’ (Preston 2008, 983). In a lone dissent, Justice Thomas simply reiterated his long-standing view that the Federal Arbitration Act does not apply to state court proceedings. Although Medtronic, Rowe, and Preston, and do not necessarily denote a trend, they shed light on Chief Justice Roberts’s and Justice Alito’s approach to preemption cases. In brief, these cases suggest that Roberts and Alito are willing to follow in the path of conservative justices on the Rehnquist Court who often sided with the states in cases concerning the commerce clause, Tenth Amendment, Eleventh Amendment and Section Five of the Fourteenth Amendment, but were prone to uphold federal authority in preemption cases (Conlan and Dudley 2005). As noted previously, the Chief Justice’s preconfirmation views on preemption are hard to discern, but the preemption cases suggest that he might be willing to find that federal law preempts very basic (and traditional) state regulatory powers. Arguably, Chief Justice Roberts’ sensitivity to states’ rights—as inferred from his off-the-bench writings—may be softened in preemption cases. Further, Justice Alito’s preconfirmation views on preemption are mainly derived from his Third Circuit New Jersey Payphone decision—there, he asserted that preemption should be viewed prudentially. Yet, by joining the majority in Rowe and Medtronic Justice Alito might be indicating that he is shifting his position to less prudential view, and hence he might be more deferential to federal power in similar cases. Yet, New Jersey Payphone presented Alito with the option, as he saw it, to decide the case based on preemption or under state law, and significantly he based his decision on the state law claim. In addition, once a preemption case has been accepted by the Supreme Court, other avenues for decision have been most likely foreclosed; that is, the Court will only consider the preemption issue. Thus, in subsequent preemption cases Justice Alito will face a stark choice: either a state law is preempted by federal law, or it is not. In the end, it may be more difficult for Justice Alito to view preemption prudentially now that he is on the Supreme Court. A few common threads in the three preemption cases are also apparent. In each case, the Court relied heavily on precedent interpreting the text of the relevant statutes, and using that approach the Court discovered clear congressional intent: such as, for example, in Rowe where Congress did not recognize a public health 592 C. Banks and J. Blakeman exception to state trucking regulations affecting delivery services, or in Preston where Congress did intend to put in place a national arbitration policy. Finally, the Court reasoned in each case that state regulations directly interfered with national policy, as defined by Congress. Thus, although Chief Justice Roberts and Justice Alito, along with six other Justices in Riegel and Preston, and with all others in Rowe, held that federal preempted state laws regulating public health, contracts, and state common law, the Court is more likely to preempt contrary state law when Congress’s intent is clearly expressed, clear Supreme Court precedent exists, and state action directly frustrates national policy. The adherence to textual moorings and congressional intent was also evident in CSX Transportation, Inc, v. Georgia State Board of Equalization (2007). As with most of the preemption rationales, the Court found consensus in addressing whether a railroad may challenge, in light of anti-tax discrimination federal law designed to protect the railroad industry, a State’s methodology in valuing CSX’s railroad property at a higher tax than analogous commercial properties. For Chief Justice Roberts and a unanimous Court, the federal law, as expressed in the so-called ‘‘4-R’’ law (the Railroad Revitalization and Regulatory Reform Act of 1976), manifested a clear congressional purpose and intent to prevent Georgia from discriminating against CSX by imposing a higher levy. Notably, in so holding the Chief Justice dismissed the State’s argument that ‘‘background principles of federalism’’ prevented courts from interfering with state tax policy decisions. In Medellin v. Texas (2008), a preemption case with a unique foreign policy twist, the Court decided by a 6:3 vote, with Justices Breyer, Ginsburg, and Souter dissenting, that state criminal courts are not bound to follow a Presidential directive implementing an International Court of Justice decision and the President’s interpretation of a treaty. In 2004, the International Court of Justice ruled in the Avena Case that the United States had violated the terms of the 1963 Vienna Convention on Consular Relations because Texas had not allowed Jose Medellin, a Mexican national, to contact his local consulate, as per the terms of the treaty, during his arrest and conviction for capital murder in the Texas criminal justice system. In response to the Avena Case decision President Bush issued a Memorandum providing that state courts give effect to the ICJ decision and comply with the Vienna Convention. Subsequently, the Texas Court of Criminal Appeals determined that the Avena Case and the Presidential Memorandum were not binding upon the states and therefore did not have to be followed in state criminal proceedings. The Court ruled in favor of the State of Texas, and the majority decision authored by Chief Justice Roberts focused on the Court’s role in interpreting international treaties. Using a strict textual analysis, the Court determined that treaties under which the United States accepts the International Court of Justice’s jurisdiction is not self-executing and thus inapplicable to the states without New Federalism Jurisprudence 593 implementing congressional legislation. Consequently, ICJ decisions are not binding upon the states either. Chief Justice Roberts’s opinion noted that the President ‘‘may not rely upon a non-self-executing treaty to establish binding rules of decision that preempt contrary state law’’ (Medellin 2008, 22). The Chief Justice’s opinion also addressed the federal government’s argument that the President has an independent source of authority to order states to comply with international law. Although the Court recognized several precedents that establish executive authority to settle claims with other sovereign states by executive agreement, it refused to stretch those cases to justify the president’s directive to state courts to follow the Avena Case decision. And, applying the tripartite framework from Justice Robert Jackson’s concurring opinion in the seminal case Youngstown Sheet and Tube v. Sawyer (1952), the Court determined that the president did not have the unilateral power to enforce state compliance with the Avena Case decision and Congress had not acquiesced in the president’s asserted foreign policy authority over the states. Thus, the Government has not identified a single instance in which the President has attempted (or Congress has acquiesced to) a Presidential directive issued to state courts, much less one that reaches deep into the heart of the State’s police powers and compels state courts to reopen final criminal judgments (Medellin 2008, 24). Justice Breyer’s dissent, joined by Justices Souter and Ginsburg, argued more forcefully that the Supremacy Clause and ‘‘the extensive case law interpreting the Clause as applied to treaties’’ indicates that the ICJ decision is binding upon state courts (Medellin 2008, 42). A few other cases, still pending, are likewise important in identifying the boundaries between state law and federal policy. In Department of Revenue of Kentucky v. Davis (2007), the Court will determine if the dormant commerce clause prohibits a state from exempting its state and local bonds from state taxation, while taxing government bonds issued outside of its borders. The Court’s decision will greatly impact state policymaking. One brief, filed by attorneys general of forty- eight states (in addition to Kentucky), argues that states have long exempted their own bonds from taxation (while taxing bonds from other states), thereby preserving their sovereign interests in regulating finance and debt service. Briefs supporting Kentucky’s tax policy also have been filed by interest groups that reflect the parochial interests of the National Governors Association and the National Conference of State Legislatures. If the Court applies the dormant commerce clause to strike down the tax policy, the ruling will directly repudiate the consensus of almost all states that operate under the principle that bond taxation policies are uniquely sovereign. In light of United Haulers Association v. Oneida-Herkimer Solid Waste Management Authority (2007), it is plausible that the justices will sustain Kentucky’s bond tax policy, especially given the near-unanimous state consensus 594 C. Banks and J. Blakeman underlying it. Also, the case invariably presents another opportunity for exacerbating judicial conflict, especially if the Chief Justice and Justice Alito opt to distance themselves from the jurisprudence of Justices Thomas and Scalia. In United Haulers, Thomas and Scalia voted with the majority to limit federal power, but they further questioned the legitimacy of the dormant commerce clause doctrine as well as its application to state economic policymaking. In contrast, dissenting Justice Alito (with Kennedy and Stevens) accepted the Court’s role in shaping dormant commerce clause doctrine as it applies to state economic policymaking, and Chief Justice Roberts (joined by the three liberal justices Souter, Ginsburg, Breyer) agreed with dormant commerce clause precedents and limited federal power based on the facts of the case. Finally, federalism cases litigated in the Roberts Court in subsequent terms may have to contend with arguments in litigant briefs adopting Justice Clarence Thomas’s interpretation of the Establishment Clause ‘‘as a federalism provision’’ in religious freedom cases. Two recent First Amendment cases, with states as litigants and amicus curiae, have adopted Justice Thomas’s federalism reading of the Establishment Clause. In Cutter v. Wilkinson (2005), which concerned the constitutionality of RLUIPA—the Religious Land Use and Institutionalized Persons Act—the State of Ohio argued that ‘‘the federalist aspect of the Establishment Clause is reflected in the basic constitutional framework’’; and that State sovereigns, when acting within their ‘‘respective sphere[s],’’ such as in matters of religion, are ‘‘not subject to federal oversight’’ (Brief of Respondent State of Ohio 2005, 53). Ohio’s position was echoed by other states as amicus curiae (Brief of the Commonwealth of Virginia 2005). Significantly, the states derived their rationales from Justice Thomas’s concurrence in Elk Grove School District v. Newdow (2004). There, he argued that the Establishment Clause is a federalism provision that imposes jurisdictional barriers to federal oversight of state religious policymaking. In its Cutter brief, the federal government vehemently disagreed; and perhaps that influenced the Court to rule unanimously in favor of RLUIPA, especially because the justices failed to address the merits of Ohio’s federalism arguments.3 Analogous federalism arguments resurfaced in the most recent church-state case of Hein v. Freedom from Religion Foundation, Inc. (2007), but this time in regards to whether a litigant had taxpayer standing to challenge the constitutionality of the White House’s Faith Based Initiative’s Office. Specifically, the State of Indiana, joined by eleven other states as amicus curiae, argued: Permissive treatment of state-taxpayer lawsuits undermines our federalist structure by involving federal courts in the daily functioning of state bureaucracies. The Court has repeatedly emphasized that federal courts must respect principles of federalism when cases portend judicial regulation of state programs . . . these same concerns apply in Establishment Clause cases, New Federalism Jurisprudence 595 which increasingly threaten to put state-government bodies under federal- court supervision (Brief of the State of Indiana and other States, as Amicus Curiae, Hein v. Freedom from Religion Foundation 2007, 13). As in Cutter, the Court ignored this federalism argument, and showed that, at least insofar as the other justices are concerned, a federalism reading of the Establishment Clause is unlikely to be adopted by the rest of the Court any time soon. Even so, the importance of this development is registered by the decision of several states to press that view on the Roberts Court, perhaps indicating that at least some of the states perceive federalism arguments as a viable, if not a fruitful, avenue to initiate change in constitutional doctrine affecting states’ rights and church–state relations. Conclusion The appointments of Chief Justice Roberts and Justice Alito probably will not appreciably reverse the recent trend of ‘‘counter-revolutionary’’ new federalism cases that impose fewer limits on federal authority. Many of the seminal states’ rights decisions were set by the Rehnquist Court, and the new Chief Justice and the addition of Justice Alito are probably not going to reconfigure the basic voting blocs and push the Court further to the right on key federalism issues. As a result, Chief Justice Roberts, as a replacement for his mentor, is likely to ‘‘stay the course’’ in new federalism cases, using minimalist principles of judicial restraint and the rule of law as pragmatic guideposts to adjudicate federalism disputes. It is an open question whether Justice Alito, in replacing Justice O’Connor, will be any more conservative than she was in those types of cases. In any event, the ‘‘States’ Rights Five,’’ although now consisting of Chief Justice Roberts, and Justices Scalia, Kennedy, Thomas, and Alito, are likely to remain intact as a solid bloc, Justice Kennedy—and not the Chief Justice or Justice Alito—will probably assume the role Justice O’Connor played as a swing vote in crafting limits on federal power. It seems unlikely that Roberts and Alito will subscribe to the federalism of Thomas and Scalia, and their failure to do so—while not putting them in the same ideological camp as Justices Ginsburg, Breyer, and Souter—may well create a wider split among the conservatives on the Court. However, in this light the new justices will have a greater effect on the interpretative lines drawn by the five-justice coalition favoring state interests. Nothing in Chief Justice Roberts’s or Justice Alito’s records indicate they will fully adopt the ideological rigidity of Justice Thomas’s originalism relative to new federalism; and, even if they did, Justices Scalia and Kennedy would have to go along in order to push the Court back toward a greater recognition of state sovereignty principles. While Justice Alito may prove to be more conservative than Justice O’Connor, he is likely to be 596 C. Banks and J. Blakeman more liberal than Justice Thomas on federalism issues. Similarly, the new Chief Justice’s decision-making is likely to resemble more that of Chief Justice Rehnquist, or Justice Scalia; and, perhaps, Justice O’Connor and Justice Thomas in certain cases. Aside from preemption cases, any constraints imposed on federal power will only develop in accordance with how well the coalition remains cohesive. In sum, the Court will continue to vindicate state power in federalism rulings but, in doing so, it remains uncertain if the justices are likely to speak with one voice in the most politically contentious cases. Notes 1. Admittedly, there is little consensus about whether ‘‘new federalism’’ jurisprudence produced solid, or even new, support for states’ rights, especially in the Rehnquist Court (Hannah 2007). Whereas Solberg and Lindquist (2006) find mixed support for correlating conservative values with judicial outcomes favoring state interests in the Rehnquist Court, Collins (2007) reports that conservative ideology explains judicial support for state and local policies. As used here, the term describes a series of decisions, epitomized by U.S. v. Lopez (1995), signaling the Court’s willingness to place greater limits on congressional commerce authority and, concomitantly, reinvigorate state sovereignty in immunity, enforcement clause, and related federalism cases (Claeys 2005). 2. Justice Clarence Thomas recused himself and did not participate in the case. 3. The Solicitor General argued that ‘‘It is too late in the day to argue that the federal Constitution contains two different Establishment Clauses with varying levels of potency’’ depending on which level of policymaking—state or federal—was at issue. Also, calling a federalism reading of Establishment a ‘‘junior varsity’’ attempt to overturn the incorporation doctrine, General Paul Clement pointed out that the Court had been asked to adopt a similar federalism reading of the Establishment Clause two decades ago in Lee v. Weisman (1992) and it chose not to do so. References Adler, Jonathan H. 2006. Reckoning with rapanos: Revisiting ‘waters of the United States’ and the limits of federal wetland regulation. Missouri Environmental Law & Policy Review 14: 1–28. Arlington Central School District Board v. Murphy, 126 S. Ct. 2455. 2006. Avena Case, 2004. 2004 I.C.J. 12. Baker, Lynn A. 2006. Federalism and the spending power from Dole to Birmingham board of education. In The Rehnquist legacy, ed. Craig Bradley. New York: Cambridge University Press. Banks, Christopher P., and John C. Blakeman. 2006. The Roberts Court and New Federalism Jurisprudence. Unpublished paper delivered at the 2006 Meeting of the American Political Science Association in Philadelphia, Pennsylvania. New Federalism Jurisprudence 597 Barbour v. Washington Metropolitan Area Transit Authority, 374 F.3d 1161. D.C. Cir. 2004. Board of Trustees of the University of Alabama v. Garrett, 531 U.S. 356. 2001. Brief of the Commonwealth of Virginia and Seven Other States, and One Territory as Amicus Curiae in Support of the Respondents, Cutter v. Wilkinson, 2005 WL 363513. 2005. Brief of Respondent State of Ohio, Cutter v. Wilkinson. 2005 WL 363713. 2005. Brief of the State of Indiana and other States, as Amicus Curiae, Hein v. Freedom from Religion Foundation, 2007 WL 62298. 2007. Central Virginia Community College v. Katz, 546 U.S. 356. 2006. Chittister v. Pennsylvania Department of Community and Economic Development, 226 F.3d 223. 3d Cir. 2000. City of Boerne v. Flores, 521 U.S. 507. 1997. Claeys, Eric R. 2005. Raich and the judicial conservativism at the close of the Rehnquist court. Lewis & Clark Law Review 9: 791–822. Clayton, Cornell W., and J. Mitchell Pickerill. 2004. Guess what happened on the way to revolution? Precursors to the supreme court’s federalism revolution. Publius: The Journal of Federalism 34 (3): 85–114. Collins, Paul M. 2007. Towards an integrated model of the U.S. supreme court’s federalism decision making. Publius: The Journal of Federalism 37 (4): 505–531. Committee on the Judiciary, U.S. Senate. 2006. Confirmation hearing on the nomination of Samuel A. Alito, Jr. to be an associate justice of the United States. S. Hrg. 109-277. 109th Cong., 2nd Sess. Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office. ———. 2005. Confirmation hearing on the nomination of John G. Roberts, Jr. to be chief justice of the United States. S.Hrg.109-158. 109th Cong., 1st Sess. Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office. ———. 2003a. Confirmation hearings on federal appointments: Hearing, part 3. S.Hrg.108-135 (Part 3). 108th Cong., 1st Sess. Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office. ———. 2003b. Confirmation hearings on federal appointments: Hearing, part 1. S.Hrg.108-135 (Part 1). 108th Cong., 1st Sess. Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office. ———. 1990. Confirmation hearings on federal appointments: Hearings on confirmation hearings on appointments to the federal judiciary, part 5.’’ S. Hrg.101-651 (Part 5). 100st Cong., 2nd Sess. Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office. Conlan, Timothy J., and Robert L. Dudley. 2005. Janus-faced federalism: State sovereignty and federal preemption in the Rehnquist court. PS: Political Science and Politics 38 (July): 363–366. CSX Transportation, Inc. v. Georgia State Board of Equalization, 128 S.Ct. 467. 2007. Cutter v. Wilkinson, 544 U.S. 709. 2005. Dinan, John. 2004. Consequences of the Rehnquist court’s federalism decisions for congressional lawmaking. Publius: The Journal of Federalism 34 (2): 39–67. 598 C. Banks and J. Blakeman Department of Revenue of Kentucky v. Davis, 127 S. Ct. 2451. 2007 (granting certiorari). Devins, Neal. 2007. Lessons from the federal partial birth abortion ban. St John’s Journal of Legal Commentary 21: 461–471. Elk Grove School District v. Newdow, 542 U.S. 1. 2004. Fortenberry, Paul Alexander, and Daniel Canton Beck. 2005. Constitutional interpretations of Article III and the commerce clause: Will the ‘hapless toad’ and ‘John Q. Public’ have any protection in the Roberts Court? University of Baltimore Journal of Environmental Law 13: 55–94. Fry v. U.S., 421 U.S. 75. 1975. Garcia v. San Antonio Metropolitan Transit Authority, 469 U.S. 528. 1985. Gonzales v. Carhart, 127 S. Ct. 1610. 2007. Gonzales v. Oregon, 546 U.S. 243. 2006. Gonzales v. Raich, 545 U.S. 1. 2005. Hannah, Jim. 2007. Forgotten law and judicial duty. Albany Law Review 70: 829–840. Harvard Law Review Association. 2006. Leading cases. Harvard Law Review 120: 351–358 (unsigned student note). Hasen, Richard L. 2005. Congressional power to renew the preclearance provisions of the voting rights act after Tennessee v. Lane. Ohio State Law Journal 66: 177–207. Hein v. Freedom from Religion Foundation, Inc., 127 S. Ct. 2553. 2007. Huhn, Wilson Ray. 2006. The constitutional jurisprudence of Sandra Day O’Connor: A refusal to ‘foreclose the unanticipated’. Akron Law Review 39: 379–415. Kimel v. Florida Board of Regents, 528 U.S. 62. 2000. Lazarus, Simon. 2006. Federalism R.I.P.? Did the Roberts hearing junk the Rehnquist court’s federalism revolution?’’ DePaul Law Review 56: 1–54. Lee v. Weisman, 505 U.S. 577. 1992. Massachusetts v. Environmental Protection Agency, 127 S. Ct. 1438. 2007. Maveety, Nancy L. 2003. Justice Sandra Day O’Connor: Accommodationism and conservatism. In Rehnquist Justice, ed. Earl M. Maltz. Lawrence, KS: University of Kansas Press. Medellin v. Texas, 76 USLW 4143. 2008. Nevada Department of Human Resources v. Hibbs, 538 U.S. 721. 2003. New Jersey Payphone Association v. Town of West New York, 299 F.3d 235. 3rd Cir. 2002. Northern Insurance Co. v. Chatham County, 547 U.S. 189. 2006. Pennhurst State School and Hospital v. Halderman, 451 U.S. 1. 1981. Preston v. Ferrer, 128 S.Ct. 978. 2008. Pushaw, Jr, Robert J. 2005. Does congress have the constitutional power to prohibit partial- birth abortion? Harvard Journal on Legislation 42: 319–353. New Federalism Jurisprudence 599 Rancho Viejo LLC v. Norton, 334 F.3d 1158. D.C. Cir. 2003. Rapanos v. U.S. Army Corps of Engineers, 126 S. Ct. 2208. 2006. Riegel v. Medtronic, Inc., 128 S. Ct. 999. 2008. Roberts, John G., Jr. 1993a. Rule of law: The new solicitor general and the power of the amicus. The Wall Street Journal (May 5, 2003): A23. ———. 1993b. Article III limits on statutory standing. Duke Law Journal 42: 1219–1232. ———. 1978a. Contract clause—legislative alteration of private pension agreements. Harvard Law Review 92: 86–99 (unsigned student note). ———. 1978b. The takings clause. Harvard Law Review 91: 1462–1501 (unsigned student note). Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113. 1973. Roper v. Simmons, 543 U.S. 551. 2005. Rowe v. New Hampshire Motor Transport Association, 128 S. Ct. 989. 2008. Schragger, Richard C. 2004. The role of the local in the doctrine and discourse of religious liberty. Harvard Law Review 117: 1810–1892. Solberg, Rorie Spill, and Stefanie A. Lindquist. 2006. Activism, ideology, and federalism: Judicial behavior in constitutional challenges before the Rehnquist court, 1986-2000. Journal of Empirical Legal Studies 3 (2): 237–261. South Dakota v. Dole, 483 U.S. 203. 1987. Tennessee v. Lane, 541 U.S. 509. 2004. Tushnet, Mark. 2006. A court divided: The Rehnquist court and the future of constitutional law. New York: W.W. Norton. ———. 2003. The new constitutional order. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. United Haulers Association v. Oneida-Herkimer Solid Waste Management Authority, 127 S. Ct. 1786. 2007. U.S. v. Georgia, 126 S.Ct. 877. 2006. U.S. v. Lopez, 514 U.S. 549. 1995. U.S. v. Morrison, 529 U.S. 598. 2000. U.S. v. Rybar, 103 F.3d 273. 3d Cir. 1996. U.S. Term Limits, Inc. v. Thornton, 514 U.S. 779. 1995. Watters v. Wachovia Bank, 127 S. Ct. 1559. 2007. Whittington, Keith E. 2001. Taking what they give us: Explaining the court’s federalism offensive. Duke Law Journal 51: 477–520. Winkelman v. Parma City School District, 127 S. Ct. 1994. 2007. Youngstown Sheet and Tube v. Sawyer, 343 U.S. 575. 1952. 600 C. Banks and J. Blakeman work_ghremggrmjhxfddwxczsilhk2a ---- wp-p1m-38.ebi.ac.uk Params is empty 404 sys_1000 exception wp-p1m-38.ebi.ac.uk no 221741787 Params is empty 221741787 exception Params is empty 2021/04/06-03:20:41 if (typeof jQuery === "undefined") document.write('[script type="text/javascript" src="/corehtml/pmc/jig/1.14.8/js/jig.min.js"][/script]'.replace(/\[/g,String.fromCharCode(60)).replace(/\]/g,String.fromCharCode(62))); // // // window.name="mainwindow"; .pmc-wm {background:transparent repeat-y top left;background-image:url(/corehtml/pmc/pmcgifs/wm-nobrand.png);background-size: auto, contain} .print-view{display:block} Page not available Reason: The web page address (URL) that you used may be incorrect. Message ID: 221741787 (wp-p1m-38.ebi.ac.uk) Time: 2021/04/06 03:20:41 If you need further help, please send an email to PMC. Include the information from the box above in your message. Otherwise, click on one of the following links to continue using PMC: Search the complete PMC archive. Browse the contents of a specific journal in PMC. Find a specific article by its citation (journal, date, volume, first page, author or article title). http://europepmc.org/abstract/MED/ work_gj7cwzebknb2to5jmdinzy4mvm ---- Homelessness: a barometer of social justice Comment www.thelancet.com/public-health Vol 5 January 2020 e2 Homelessness: a barometer of social justice The number of people experiencing homelessness in the UK has dramatically increased since 2010. In the autumn of 2018, 4677 people in England were estimated to be sleeping rough, a worrying increase from 1768 in 2010.1 Although these numbers almost certainly underestimate the total number of people affected, the trends in these data are important and unsurprising, given that one in five bed spaces for single homeless people have been lost during the same period, a reduction from 43 655 in 2010 to 34 900 in 2018.2 Rough sleeping is at the extreme and visible end of homelessness, and estimates of the total number of people affected by the UK’s housing crisis highlight an even larger problem. Data from 2019 suggest that around 250 000 households and 400 000 people are currently homeless or at risk of homelessness.3 Homelessness can have fatal consequences. The UK Office for National Statistics (ONS) estimated that 726 people experiencing homelessness died in England and Wales in 2018.4 These figures represent a 22% year- to-year increase and are the highest since these estimates began in 2013. The ONS data suggest that most deaths among people who were homeless were caused by drug- related poisoning, suicide, and alcohol-specific deaths. Like estimates of the number of people who are sleeping rough, these data are likely to underestimate deaths, but the trend is important and provides a rare insight into the precarious health of this population. Our recent study of deaths among people experiencing homelessness showed a different pattern of deaths to that of the ONS data.5 We examined the causes of death among people previously admitted to hospital and seen by specialist integrated homeless health and care schemes. Similar to the ONS data, we found high numbers of deaths caused by drug-related poisoning, suicide, and alcohol. However, our study highlighted the importance of chronic and potentially preventable diseases, such as coronary heart disease, respiratory disease, and cancer. Crucially, after adjusting for age and sex, nearly one in three of the deaths among people who were homeless in our study were due to causes that are amenable to timely health care.5 Collectively, this evidence demonstrates a public health emergency that we already know how to tackle— but have failed to do so. Most people experiencing homelessness had been admitted to hospital in acute health crisis.5 Their health needs represent a system failure to intervene early and prevent serious harms. Evidence from England, corroborated internationally, highlights multiple missed opportunities for timely intervention. First, the unsafe discharging of patients who are homeless must be stopped. Safeguarding Adults Reviews into the deaths of people who are homeless have highlighted poor hospital discharge practices, including people being discharged back onto the street.6 Health-care professionals have a duty of care and should apply the same standards of quality and safety to all patients; for example, discharge should be delayed when it is not safe.7 Discharging a patient without them having somewhere safe to stay is a safeguarding issue. Second, specialist integrated homeless health schemes are more effective and cost-effective than standard care.8 Despite large increases in homelessness and deaths among people who are homeless, many of these specialist schemes closed because of an absence of sustainable funding. The case for reinvesting in and scaling up these services nationally is clear. Third, intermediate care facilities in the community can prevent serious illness and unplanned hospital admissions, saving lives and money.8 These services play a vital role in freeing up acute beds, while ensuring that people still get the help and support they need to manage long-term conditions and plan for their future. These services need to be widely accessible to both community and hospital health-care providers as part of specialist integrated homeless health schemes, and all of these services should be designed collaboratively to ensure they are accessible to, and meet the needs of, people experiencing homelessness.9 Fourth, we need to move away from emergency hostels and unaffordable or unsustainable private lettings to adopt a full housing-first approach to homelessness. People who become homeless should have rapid access to permanent housing with ongoing health and social care support that recognises the complex needs of individuals who have experienced long periods of severe adversity.10 This approach to housing should be accompanied by a large increase in social housing to reduce the number of people at risk of homelessness. Finally, we must tackle Published Online December 2, 2019 https://doi.org/10.1016/ S2468-2667(19)30240-3 http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1016/S2468-2667(19)30240-3&domain=pdf Comment e3 www.thelancet.com/public-health Vol 5 January 2020 the political determinants of homelessness, including child poverty, poor education and employment oppor- tunities, criminalisation, invisibility, and stigma. Everyone has a right to dignity and respect. Home- lessness is a barometer of social justice that reflects a serious problem in our society, the remedy to which is within our grasp. Rob Aldridge Institute of Health Informatics, University College London, London NW1 2DA, UK r.aldridge@ucl.ac.uk I declare no competing interests. Copyright © 2019 The Author(s). Published by Elsevier Ltd. This is an Open Access article under the CC BY 4.0 license. 1 UK Ministry of Housing, Communities & Local Government. Rough sleeping statistics: autumn 2018, England (revised). Feb 25, 2019. https://assets.publishing.service.gov.uk/government/ uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/781567/Rough_ Sleeping_Statistics_2018_release.pdf (accessed Nov 20, 2019). 2 Homeless Link. Annual review of single homelessness support in England. https://www.homeless.org.uk/facts/our-research/annual- review-of-single-homelessness-support-in-england (accessed Nov 20, 2019). 3 National Housing Federation. How many people need a social rented home? September, 2019. http://s3-eu-west-1.amazonaws.com/img. housing.org.uk/NHF_Briefing_How_many_people_need_a_social_ rented_home_FINAL.pdf (accessed Nov 20, 2019). 4 Office for National Statistics. Deaths of homeless people in England and Wales: 2018. Oct 1, 2019. https://www.ons.gov.uk/ peoplepopulationandcommunity/birthsdeathsandmarriages/deaths/ bulletins/deathsofhomelesspeopleinenglandandwales/2018 (accessed Nov 21, 2019). 5 Aldridge RW, Menezes D, Lewer D, et al. Causes of death among homeless people: a population-based cross-sectional study of linked hospitalisation and mortality data in England. Wellcome Open Res 2019; 4: 49. 6 Martineau S, Cornes M, Manthorpe J, Ornelas B, Fuller J. Safeguarding, homelessness and rough sleeping: an analysis of Safeguarding Adults Reviews. Sept 3, 2019. https://kclpure.kcl.ac.uk/portal/files/116649790/ SARs_and_Homelessness_HSCWRU_Report_2019.pdf (accessed Nov 20, 2019). 7 Cornes M, Aldridge R, Tinelli M, et al. Transforming out-of-hospital care for people who are homeless: support tool complementing the high impact change model for transfers between hospital and home. Nov 18, 2019. https://kclpure.kcl.ac.uk/portal/files/119151993/HHD_SUPPORT_TOOL_ Nov_2019.pdf (accessed Nov 20, 2019). 8 King’s College London. Effectiveness and cost-effectiveness of ‘usual care’ versus ‘specialist integrated care’: a comparative study of hospital discharge arrangements for homeless people in England. https://www.kcl. ac.uk/scwru/res/hrp/hrp-studies/hospitaldischarge (accessed Nov 21, 2019). 9 Nobody Left Outside. NLO checklist guidance document. October, 2019. https://nobodyleftoutside.eu/nlo-checklist-guidance-document (accessed Nov 22, 2019). 10 Baxter AJ, Tweed EJ, Katikireddi SV, Thomson H. Effects of Housing First approaches on health and well-being of adults who are homeless or at risk of homelessness: systematic review and meta-analysis of randomised controlled trials. J Epidemiol Community Health 2019; 73: 379–87. Homelessness: a barometer of social justice References work_gjvqovgtdbgyvbtehrkl5thdfe ---- Future of Youth Justice in Japan Masahiro Suzuki1; Kenji Takeuchi2 1 School of Criminology and Criminal Justice, Griffith University, Brisbane, Australia 2 Faculty of Law, Kyushu University, Fukuoka, Japan Corresponding Author Name: Masahiro Suzuki Position: Doctoral candidate Affiliation: School of Criminology and Criminal Justice, Griffith University, Brisbane, Australia Tel: +61 (0)7 3735 1202 Email: masahiro.suzuki@griffithuni.edu.au Published in Youth Justice, doi: 10.1177/1473225419869988. https://protect-au.mimecast.com/s/XFVyCyoNQ6C4ojYPIMoTBK?domain=doi.org 1 Abstract Japanese youth justice has experienced several reforms to date. Currently, a radical revision is under consideration: to lower the age of criminal majority from 20 years to 18 years. Japanese scholars and practitioners have since been engaged in debates over this proposal. Drawing on existing empirical research on youth offending and juvenile justice, the purpose of this paper is to advance a critical analysis on (in)appropriateness of lowering the age of criminal majority. By focusing on its potential consequences, we also discuss what the future of youth justice in Japan would look like. We conclude with offering research implications. Keywords Youth justice, Japan, age of criminal majority, juvenile law, youth offending 2 Introduction The age of criminal majority varies between countries. For example, according to Abrams, Jordan, and Montero (2018; also see Pruin and Dünkel, 2015 for other countries in Europe, and Thomas, 2017 for the US), who recently examined what defines as young offenders in the justice systems of Argentina, Belize, UK, and Finland, the age of criminal majority ranges from 16 years to 21 years. In Japan, since its enactment in 1948, the Juvenile Law defines the age of criminal majority as under 20 years. The Japanese government is currently considering revising this threshold. It proposes to lower the age of criminal majority from 20 years to 18 years (Ellis and Kyo, 2017). This proposal has caused a heated debate over its justification and appropriateness. Specifically, Japanese scholars and lawyers have raised grave concerns about this radical change (Japan Federation of Bar Associations, 2015; 2018; 2019; Japanese Criminal Law Scholars, 2015; 2018; The Japanese Society of Psychiatry and Neurology, 2019). We aim to add to this debate in Japan. By drawing on existing empirical research on juvenile justice and youth offending, our objective is to conduct a critical analysis on lowering the age of criminal majority in Japan. Inspired by Haines and Case (2018), with a focus on its potential consequences, we also discuss what the future of youth justice in Japan would look like if the age of criminal majority were lowered. Similar to other East Asian countries, such as China (Hebenton and Jou, 2010), criminology is a subfield of law in Japan (Konishi, 2013). Most criminologists in Japan have a law background. Legal perspectives tend to dominate the debates on lowering the age of criminal majority in Japan. There is a lack of focus on important and relevant perspectives, such as developmental psychology and other behavioural and social sciences, including criminology. Examining potential consequences on the basis of existing evidence on youth 3 offending and juvenile justice will offer an important contribution to advancing the discussion over revising the threshold of the age of criminal majority in Japan. In the youth justice literature, defining the age threshold for the juvenile justice system has been a major topic of discussion (e.g. McDiarmid, 2013). For example, researchers have argued the necessity of raising the minimum age of criminal responsibility in the UK (Goldson, 2013) and Australia (Cunneen, 2017), and the ‘raise the age’ movement has been occurring in the US (Cauffman et al., 2017). Internationally, youth justice scholars and practitioners have advocated for expanding the scope of juvenile justice. With the proposed reform to lower the age of criminal majority from 20 years to 18 years, Japanese youth justice attempts to narrow down its scope. In this sense, discussing Japanese youth justice adds to the youth justice literature as an interesting example in the international context. The structure of this paper is as follows. First, we briefly describe the history of reforms in Japanese youth justice, as well as the current proposed revision. Second, we provide the debates over lowering the age of criminal majority in Japan. In particular, we introduce the pros and cons that have been offered in Japanese literature. Third, drawing on existing empirical research on youth offending and juvenile justice, we critically analyse the (in)appropriateness and potential consequences of lowering the age of criminal majority. Finally, we conclude by discussing the future of youth justice in Japan and by providing future research implications. Reforms of Youth Justice in Japan History of Reforms Japanese youth justice has experienced several reforms. These revisions have already been discussed elsewhere (for example, see Ellis and Kyo, 2017; Suzuki and Otani, 2017), and these past revisions are not the main focus of this paper. Therefore, we briefly review the 4 history of reforms in youth justice in Japan. The Japanese Juvenile Law has been revised four times to date. Below we describe the main changes of each revision. The first revision of the Juvenile Law in Japan occurred in 2000. This involved the following three main changes (Hoffmann, 2007; Schwarzenegger, 2003; Yoshida, 2003). First, the minimum age of criminal responsibility was lowered from 16 years to 14 years, and serious crimes, such as intentional homicide, were determined to be automatically transferred to the adult court. Second, this revision introduced a panel of judges in youth justice and enabled the involvement of prosecutors in the adjudication process of the Family Court for serious cases. Finally, victims were allowed to access the court records and offer their statements to the youth justice proceedings. In 2007, the second revision of the Juvenile Law was conducted. Several changes were made at this time (Osaki, 2017; Takumi, 2017). These included the expansion of police investigations on status offences; lowering the minimum age for juvenile reformatory schools from over 14 years to around over 12 years; introduction of more penalties for a breach of a probation order; and the introduction of court-assigned counsel for serious crimes committed by a young offender. The Juvenile Law in Japan was again changed in 2008. This revision mainly concerned with victim rights (Matsui, 2011). In relation to the 2000 revision on access to court records and victim statements, victim rights were expanded and strengthened. Further, victims were allowed to participate in the Family Court hearings. The fourth and most recent revision was conducted in 2014. This revision was mainly related to sentencing (Ellis and Kyo, 2017). For example, the upper limit for custodial sentences was increased from 15 years to 20 years. The condition of parole was also tightened so that it required a longer period before eligibility. 5 The Juvenile Law in Japan has been revised as discussed above. The common theme among these reforms is that it was revised in a punitive way (Kuzuno, 2005). Inconsistent with the aim of the Juvenile law—to protect juveniles—young offenders, particularly those who commit a serious crime, now receive more severe punishments. As Suzuki and Otani (2017, p. 168) noted, ‘the notion of parens patriae, long maintained in the Japanese youth justice, seems to be declining’. The Current Proposed Revision In addition to these past reforms, another revision is currently under consideration. The Japanese government proposes to lower the age of criminal majority from 20 years to 18 years. This proposal is not entirely new. Since the enactment of the current Juvenile Law, lowering the age of criminal majority has been advocated several times, particularly by prosecutors in the 1960s and1970s. However, it was never implemented because its justification that youth crime was worsening was found to be wrong during the legislative council that discussed this proposal (Saito, 2018; Takeuchi, 2017b). We elaborate on two main reasons why this revision is again proposed. The first and foremost reason is the revision of the Public Offices Election Law (Japanese Ministry of Justice, 2016; Osaki, 2017; Takumi, 2017). In 2015, the right to vote was lowered from 20 years to 18 years. The supplementary provision of this revised law required legislators to consider also revising the civil law because the civil law in Japan defines 20 years as an adult, which was the reason why the right to vote was set at 20. This provision also requested legislators to take other necessary legislative measures. As a result, the Japanese government has started considering lowering the age of criminal majority from 20 years to 18 years to maintain consistency among laws. Another reason for this proposal is the tough on (youth) crime policy (Japanese Criminal Law Scholars, 2015; Kawade, 2015; Sasaki, 2016). The most apparent example is the remark 6 by the then Chairperson of the Policy Research Council in the ruling party, the Liberal Democracy Party of Japan, that it is necessary to consider revising the Juvenile Law in order to address the increasingly serious nature of youth offending. As is evident in the past reforms of youth justice in Japan (Fenwick, 2013; Ryan, 2005), lowering the age of criminal majority in Japan is proposed as part of increasing punitiveness in the Japanese criminal justice policy (Fenwick, 2013; Hamai and Ellis, 2008; Miyazawa, 2008). Debates over Lowering the Age of Criminal Majority in Japan The proposal of lowering the age of criminal majority in Japan has caused a heated debate among scholars and practitioners in youth justice. Once it is approved, it will be arguably one of the most radical revisions to transform Japanese youth justice, in the sense of who qualifies as ‘youth’ offenders. In this section, we introduce the debates over lowering the age of criminal majority in Japan. We focus on the pros and cons that have been offered in Japanese literature. Pros To discuss the proposal of lowering the age of criminal majority in Japan, the Japanese Ministry of Justice has formed a study group consisting of scholars and government officials (Japanese Ministry of Justice, 2016). This study group interviewed experts involved in youth justice and juvenile law, lawyers, victim support groups and media, and sought public opinions and examined current juvenile justice and youth offending in Japan. Subsequently, it published a report summarising the overall discussion. As some scholars, such as Takumi (2017) and Osaki (2017) observed, this report outlines reasons for justifying lowering the age of criminal majority in Japan (Japanese Ministry of Justice, 2016). The major reason for its justification is to maintain consistency with other laws (Japanese Ministry of Justice, 2016). As discussed above, as a consequence of the revision of the right 7 to vote in the Public Offices Election Law, other laws, such as the civil law, will also redefine an adult as 18 years. The advocates of lowering the age of criminal majority argue that people over 18 years who are considered adults in the civil law should not be eligible for the Juvenile Law in terms of the notion of parens patriae. In light of paternalism that governs the criminal justice system in Japan (c.f. Foote, 1992), it is considered that those who are defined as an adult should not receive protection of the Juvenile Law as children (see also a discussion in the legislative council of the Japanese Ministry of Justice, Hoseishingikai, 2018). They also suggest that consistency between laws would help to promote understanding among the public in terms of the legal definition of an adult in Japan. They claim that it is important to raise the awareness of and hold accountable young people who are above 18 as an adult in the criminal justice system. To strengthen this argument, the advocates provide examples of other countries that define 18 years as an adult offender (Japanese Ministry of Justice, 2016). In addition to these reasons, the advocates of lowering the age of criminal majority claim that increased recidivism as a potential consequence of lowering the age of criminal majority can be addressed by taking new measures for young adult offenders aged 18–19 years (Japanese Ministry of Justice, 2016). For example, they suggest introducing a new punishment that allows young adult offenders to be accommodated in juvenile reformatory schools, or new rehabilitation programs that offer special treatments in the adult correction facilities. They also propose to prepare a special measure for re-entry support, such as coordination with relevant agencies for housing and employment (Japanese Ministry of Justice, 2016). Cons In contrast to the endorsement for lowering the age of criminal majority in Japan, there are strong criticisms against lowering the age of criminal majority in Japan. Juvenile law and 8 youth justice scholars in Japan have raised grave concerns (Japan Federation of Bar Associations, 2015; 2018; Japanese Criminal Law Scholars, 2015; 2018) because the proposed revision does not align with the philosophy, history, purpose, and practice of youth justice and Juvenile Law in Japan. Japanese scholars have offered the critique that maintaining consistency among laws cannot justify lowering the age of criminal majority because it is not consistent with the legislative intent of the Juvenile Law to protect and rehabilitate young offenders (Goto, 2015). They go on to argue that reflecting its legal purposes, different laws should be able to set different ages to define an adult (Maruyama, 2017; Saito, 2018; Takeuchi, 2017a). In fact, as Abe and Yamazaki (2018) have observed, the Japanese government plans to continue restricting access to smoking, drinking and gambling among people under 20 years. Such restrictions are reflections and evidence of paternalism, which the Japanese government considers necessary for protecting these young people who are currently eligible for the Juvenile Law (Japan Federation of Bar Associations, 2018). Another critique is based on a historical perspective of the Juvenile Law in Japan. In the past, inconsistency between laws regarding the age of majority existed in Japan (Washino, 2017). While the civil law defined 20 years as an adult, the old Juvenile Law set the age of criminal majority as 18 years. After World War 2, when the current Juvenile Law was enacted, the age of criminal majority was raised from 18 years to 20 years (Maruyama, 2017; Moriya, 2018). It is important to note here that this revision of raising the age of criminal majority was conducted not because of the need to maintain consistency between laws. Instead, the age of criminal majority was raised because it was recognised that offenders under 20 years are still transitioning into adulthood, and therefore requiring protection because of their developmental needs (Takeuchi, 2015b). 9 Japanese scholars also criticise against lowering the age of criminal majority by giving examples of other countries that define the age of criminal majority as 18 years. This is not only because there are also countries whose age of criminal majority is 21 years (Abe and Yamazaki, 2018). But also, as Takeuchi (2017b) has observed, even if the age of criminal majority is 18 years, some of these countries, such as Germany, offer special proceedings and treatment for young adult offenders aged 18–21 years because there is consensus that they are more equivalent to young offenders than adult offenders in their maturity. The strongest criticism against lowering the age of criminal majority in Japan is derived from a rehabilitative perspective. This concern is especially raised in the event of a minor crime. According to Takeuchi (2017a) who analysed the Japanese youth justice system, minor crimes are the most common crime committed by senior young offenders who would become ineligible for the Juvenile Law after the proposed revision. Takeuchi (2017a) observed that these minor crimes, such as theft and assault, are currently handled in accordance with the aim of the Juvenile Law. Even if young offenders commit a minor crime, for which adult offenders would receive only a suspended prosecution or fine, these young offenders need to undergo a clinical assessment governed by the Family Court and receive necessary treatments. In practice, Japanese youth justice is operated with this rehabilitative focus. In this sense, youth justice in Japan is not necessarily ‘soft’ on youth crime (Abe and Yamazaki, 2018), as the politicians claim. However, lowering the age of criminal majority would result in these young offenders in need receiving a criminal record (Abe and Yamazaki, 2018; Japanese Criminal Law Scholars, 2018) instead of receiving appropriate treatment (Kawade, 2015; Takeuchi, 2015a). This potential consequence does not align with the purpose of the Juvenile Law—to give a second chance to young offenders (Otsuka, 2018). 10 (In)Appropriateness of Lowering the Age of Criminal Majority The preceding section has provided the current debates over lowering the age of criminal majority in Japan. In this section, we critically analyse the (in)appropriateness of lowering the age of criminal majority in Japan. To do so, we discuss whether this proposed revision of lowering the age of criminal majority in Japan is in line with established knowledge based on existing empirical research on juvenile justice and youth offending. Because the debates over lowering the age of criminal majority in Japan tend to be limited to legal perspectives, examining its potential consequences on the basis of existing empirical evidence on youth offending and juvenile justice will shed new light on the debates. We focus on the characteristics of young offenders and the potential consequences of changing the age of criminal majority. Characteristics of Young Offenders Evidence shows that young offenders differ from adult offenders. First, young offenders only have limited comprehensibility. The most well-known research is by Grisso (1981; Grisso et al., 2003). Examining the level of understanding of Miranda warnings, Grisso’s research has demonstrated that youths younger than 15 years, or those with IQ scores below 80, have difficulties properly understanding their legal rights. This finding is consistent with the results in recent research (e.g. Eatwood et al., 2015; Zelle et al., 2015). This challenge facing young offenders is also recognised by lawyers. Interviewing attorneys in Canada, Viljoen et al. (2010) found they had faced challenges when defending juvenile offenders; they had encountered cases that made them question whether young offenders correctly understood the legal process and consequences of their decision-making. Young offenders feel this difficulty in the youth justice process. Lount et al. (2018) examined how young offenders experienced and perceived youth justice in New Zealand. Their findings 11 highlighted that, due to their low verbal ability, young offenders felt disadvantaged in the justice process because they had difficulties understanding the legal terms used. Another distinction between young and adult offenders is their level of psychosocial maturity (Cauffman and Steinberg, 2000; Steinberg and Cauffman, 1996). Young offenders have a diminished ability of judgement because they are more impulsive and often cannot consider future consequences in their decision-making. In other words, young offenders tend to be risk-takers (Steinberg, 2008) and sensation-seekers (Steinberg et al., 2008). This characteristic is evident in their decision to become involved in anti-social behaviours (Cauffman et al., 2016). Examining the effect of psychosocial maturity on antisocial decision-making, Modecki (2008, p. 88) has found that ‘adolescents are less mature on the judgment . . . relative to college students, young-adults, and adults’. Similar results are reported in other research (e.g. Bryan-Hancock and Casey, 2010). Young offenders are still in the human developmental process. For this reason, young offenders need a different justice system that offers special treatment and care. This difference between young and adult offenders is the reason why the ‘raise the age’ movement has been occurring in the US (Cauffman et al., 2017; Justice Policy Institute, 2017; Thomas, 2017). While the age of criminal majority is 18 years in most states, in several states, such as New York (Raise the Age NY, n.d.), the age of criminal majority is still lower than 18 years (Arya, 2011). Along with this ‘raise the age’ movement, some states, such as Louisiana (Louisiana Youth Justice Coalition, 2016), have already successfully raised the age of criminal majority to 18 (Williams, 2015). Several scholars have further argued that young adult offenders aged 18–24 years are more comparable to younger offenders (Cauffman, 2012; Farrington et al., 2012; Feld, 2018; Prior et al., 2011), thereby claiming that these young adult offenders should be treated similarly, or that special courts and correctional facilities should be established for them 12 (Farrington et al., 2012; Loeber et al., 2012; Loomis-Gustafson, 2017). Young adult offenders tend to have the same characteristics, as well as face the same challenges in the justice procedures, as younger offenders. Examining experiences of young adult offenders (18–25 years) in the criminal justice system in Hong Kong, Cheng and Leung (2018) have found that they also faced difficulties similar to those described above, such as lack of understanding of their legal rights and of the legal process. This is congruent with the research conducted in the UK, showing that young adult offenders experienced challenges understanding the legal terminology used in the criminal justice procedure (Centre for Justice Innovation, 2018). If young offenders receive different treatment in a different justice system due to their immaturity, young adult offenders may also need such care because they may be more like young offenders than adult offenders. In sum, given the differences between young and adult offenders, lowering the age of criminal majority from 20 years to 18 years in Japan does not align with the evidence on the characteristics of young offenders. Considering similarities between young and young adult offenders, this proposed revision is, rather, moving in the opposite direction to the evidence. It may result in young offenders losing opportunities to receive appropriate treatment, consequently leading them to reoffending. Potential Consequences of Lowering the Age of Criminal Majority As discussed above, one of the justifications for lowering the age of criminal majority in Japan is that the current Juvenile Law is ‘soft’ on youth crime. By punishing young offenders more severely, it intends to prevent youth offending. However, due to the revision in the Juvenile Law, serious youth crimes are already transferred to the adult criminal justice system in Japan. More importantly, there is no evidence that this juvenile transfer can prevent youth crime in terms of both specific and general deterrence. 13 As for specific deterrence by juvenile transfer, many studies have been conducted. Therefore, there exist several systematic reviews and meta-analyses. According to the systematic review conducted by the Task Force on Community Preventive Services, the juvenile transfer is more likely to increase reoffending among transferred youths than among those not transferred (Hahn et al., 2007; McGowan et al., 2007). While the number of studies included is small, the meta-analysis conducted by the Washington State Institute for Public Policy (2014) also indicates that juvenile transfer is related to an increased likelihood of recidivism. Similarly, in the most recent meta-analysis, Zane, Welsh, and Mears (2016, p. 915) have reported that juvenile transfer may lead to ‘a small but statistically nonsignificant increase in future offending’. While cautioning the interpreting of the overall finding, they have suggested that juvenile transfer ‘does not result in an overall reduction in recidivism and may even increase it’. Thus, the systematic reviews on and meta-analyses of the specific deterrence effect by juvenile transfer consistently show that juvenile transfer is likely to increase recidivism or at least have no effect on preventing it. With regards to general deterrence through juvenile transfer, because of an insufficient number of studies, neither systematic reviews nor meta-analyses has been conducted (Hahn et al., 2007; McGowan et al., 2007). However, existing research consistently shows that juvenile transfer is not likely to have a deterrent effect on youth crime. The most recent research has been conducted by Steiner et al. (2006), who examined the general deterrence effect of juvenile transfer laws in 22 states in the US. Consistent with the past few studies (Jensen and Metsger, 1994; Risler et al., 1998; Singer and McDowall, 1988), their findings have demonstrated that juvenile transfer has no impact on deterring youth crime. Other, but limited, research has directly explored the impact of revising the age of criminal majority on youth offending. The study conducted by Fowler and Kurlychek (2018) is one such study. In this research, focusing on the fact that the age of criminal majority in 14 Connecticut was raised from 16 years to 17 years in 2010, they conducted a natural experiment. Comparing 16-year-old offenders who were processed as adult offenders before the legislative change and those who were processed as young offenders after the change, they examined the recidivism in a two-year follow-up period. They found that those treated as young offenders were less likely to reoffend than those treated as adult offenders (Fowler and Kurlychek, 2018). However, the findings of research conducted by Loeffler and Grunwald (2015) have shown otherwise. Because Illinois also raised the age of criminal majority from 17 years to 18 years in 2010, they also conducted a natural experiment. In this study, they compared the rearrest rates between 17-year-old offenders who experienced youth justice after the change and those who experienced the adult justice system before it. Their finding has demonstrated that raising the criminal majority had no impact on recidivism. This remains the case even when they considered subsamples of those ‘arrested within 60 days of their 17th or 18th birthday’ as well as ‘those arrested within 60 days of the change in law’, in order to ensure the robustness of their findings (Loeffler and Grunwald, 2015, p. 363). In addition to these studies on the specific deterrence effect, Loeffler and Chalfin (2017) have examined the general deterrence effect of raising the age of criminal majority. They also focused on Connecticut, but they also included the data up to 2013 because in Connecticut the age of criminal majority was again raised from 17 years to 18 years in 2012. To examine the impact of raising the age of criminal majority on the overall youth crime rate, based on the official crime data they created a hypothetical state whose youth crime rate resembled that in Connecticut before the change in the age of criminal majority in 2010. Comparing youth crime between Connecticut and this hypothetical state, they found that raising the age of criminal majority had no impact on deterring youth crime. 15 The above three studies have examined the impact of raising the age of criminal majority on youth offending, not that of lowering the age of criminal majority. One may question their relevance to this paper. In our view, however, the above findings may have an important implication about lowering the age of criminal majority.1 Although it remains speculative at this stage, changing the age of criminal majority might not have an impact on youth crime. This implication may be even more important because such null effects are seen even for raising the age of criminal majority, which is a beneficial revision for young offenders. As Loeffler and Grunwald (2015) phrased it (although their argument was about raising the age of criminal majority), this implication may be unexpected to both advocates for and opponents of lowering the age of criminal majority in Japan. If lowering the age of criminal majority did not impact on youth crime, it would not support either side of the claims. But, when considering the consequences of lowering the age of criminal majority, it is necessary to look beyond its effect on youth offending. For example, as Farrington et al. (2017) have suggested in the context of raising the age of criminal majority, lowering the age of criminal majority may lead to a loss of an opportunity for young offenders to receive appropriate treatment and rehabilitation when needed. A related point is that lowering the age of criminal majority may also negatively influence the future of offenders, particularly in terms of employment. Particularly 1 Following the ‘raise the age’ movement, several cost-benefit analyses have been conducted in US, and they consistently indicated that the benefits of raising the age of criminal majority would outweigh its costs (Deitch et al., 2012; Henrichson and Levshin, 2011; Hornby Zeller Associates, 2018; Independent Democratic Conference, 2016). If raising the age of criminal majority did not have an impact or only had a limited impact on youth crime in terms of both specific and general deterrence, these estimates might have overestimated its benefits because even as a conservative estimate, these cost-benefit analyse anticipated 10% reduction of recidivism (for example, see Deitch et al., 2012; Henrichson and Levshin, 2011). 16 problematic may be a criminal record because, unlike youth justice, a record is not expunged in the adult criminal justice system. It may influence their future employment (Illinois Juvenile Justice Commission, 2013; Justice Policy Institute, 2017; Loomis-Gustafson, 2017). The negative impact of a criminal record on employment among other outcomes, such as recidivism, is well known (e.g. Denver, 2017). Indeed, existing research on juvenile transfer shows that undergoing the adult criminal justice system rather than in the youth justice system is linked to diminished opportunities for employment as well as to reduced income (Augustyn and Loughran, 2017; Sharlein, 2018; Taylor, 2015). Another problem of lowering the age of criminal majority may be the negative consequences of accommodating younger offenders in adult correction facilities (Cauffman et al., 2017). Compared to juvenile facilities, there tend to be fewer services available for rehabilitation in adult correctional facilities (Kupchik, 2007; Ng et al., 2012). This may be problematic because the lack of support for reintegration is noted as one of the possible reasons for the increased likelihood of reoffending by juvenile transfer (Redding, 2008). Research has also shown that younger offenders incarcerated in adult prisons are more likely to be depressed (Murrie et al., 2009; Ng et al., 2011). Additionally, young offenders incarcerated in adult prisons may be more likely to be physically or sexually assaulted (Forst and Fagan, 1989; National Prison Rape Elimination Commission, 2009). The Future of Youth Justice in Japan: Promising or Precarious? If the age of criminal majority were lowered, what would the future of youth justice in Japan look like? According to the extant literature on youth offending and juvenile justice, we expect that it would likely be precarious rather than promising. Given the differences between young and adult offenders, lowering the age of criminal majority does not align with existing evidence on the characteristics of young offenders. Although studies on the impacts 17 of changing the age of criminal majority on youth offending are limited, coupled with the research on juvenile transfer, these studies imply that lowering the age of criminal majority may be less likely to provide benefits in terms of deterring youth crime. Lowering the age of criminal majority in Japan may raise other problems, such as diminished future opportunities for employment and negative consequences of incarceration with older prisoners. Overall, based on existing evidence, we assume that lowering the age of criminal majority is more likely to bring about negative consequences for youth justice in Japan. However, a limitation exists in our argument because the majority of empirical studies we have relied on to build our argument have been conducted in the US. There are differences between Japan and the US in terms of how the youth justice systems operate. For instance, research suggested that ethnic minorities are more likely to be transferred to the adult court in the US (Brown and Sorensen, 2013). The quantity of young offenders who are transferred to the adult court in Japan is also different from those in the US because the annual number of serious crimes that are eligible for juvenile transfer cases in Japan is much lower than that in the US (for example, see Homusogokenkyujo, 2007). There is also a distinction in terms of age thresholds for youth justice. This difference may be of particular importance because the age of criminal majority in Japan would be 18 years even if it were lowered, whereas the age of criminal majority in most US states would be 18 years even if it were raised. Given these differences, the findings of the above studies may not necessarily apply to youth offending and juvenile justice in Japan. Despite these limitations, we strongly recommend against lowering the age of criminal majority in Japan and argue that this proposed revision will not benefit youth justice in Japan. As we have discussed, the proposal to lower the age of criminal majority in Japan has emerged mainly out of the need to maintain consistency between laws, in particular recently with the civil law, which was determined to redefine adults as 18 years (Japanese Criminal 18 Law Scholars, 2018). The proponents for this revision do not carefully consider existing knowledge on youth offending and juvenile justice. Despite the past reforms driven by punitivism (Fenwick, 2013; Hamai and Ellis, 2008; Miyazawa, 2008), Japanese youth justice has maintained its rehabilitative focus and been successful in reintegrating young offenders in practice (Ellis and Kyo, 2017). The emphasis on and success of rehabilitation in youth justice are recognised even in the study group formed by the Japanese Ministry of Justice to discuss lowering the age of criminal majority (Japanese Ministry of Justice, 2016). However, lowering the age of criminal majority might be radical enough to transform youth justice in Japan into something entirely different. Given the recent discussions in the legislative council in Japan that do not consider the knowledge we drew upon, but emphasise the importance of consistency between laws, we are pessimistic about whether the critique will be taken into account. We anticipate that lowering the age of criminal majority is likely. This will be unfortunate for youth justice in Japan. What we can and should do is examine its impact on juvenile justice and youth offending in Japan. Compared to not only other industrialised countries but also to other East Asian countries, Japan has fewer empirical studies in criminology (for example, see Suzuki et al., 2018). The reforms in the justice system in Japan have been implemented without giving a lot of thought to whether the revisions are moving in the right direction in light of empirical knowledge on youth offending and juvenile justice. Similarly, after reforms were conducted, little research has been conducted to evaluate the effectiveness of the reforms. Japan should step out of this vicious cycle and start developing evidence-based youth justice (Haines and Case, 2018). 19 References Abe Y and Yamazaki H (2018) Shonenho tekiyonenrei no hikisage nitsuite kangaeru. Katei no Ho to Saiban 16: 57-70 (in Japanese). Abrams L S, Jordan S P and Montero L A (2018) What is a juvenile? A cross-national comparison of youth justice systems. Youth Justice 18(2): 111-130. Arya N (2011) Legislative victories from 2005 to 2010: Removing youth from the adult criminal justice system. Washington D.C.: Campaign for Youth Justice. Augustyn M B and Loughran T A (2017) Juvenile waiver as a mechanism of social stratification: A focus on human capital. Criminology 55(2): 405-437. Brown J M and Sorensen J R (2013) Race, ethnicity, gender, and waiver to adult court. Journal of Ethnicity in Criminal Justice 11(3): 181-195. Bryan-Hancock C and Casey S (2010) Psychological maturity of at-risk juveniles, young adults and adults: Implications for the justice system. Psychiatry, Psychology and Law 17(1): 57-69. Cauffman E (2012) Aligning justice system processing with developmental science. Criminology & Public Policy 11(4): 751-758. Cauffman E, Cavanagh C, Donley S and Thomas A G (2016) A developmental perspective on adolescent risk-taking and criminal behavior. In: Piquero A R (ed.), The handbook of criminological theory. Surrey, UK: Wiley-Blackwell, 100-120. Cauffman E, Donley S and Thomas A (2017) Raising the age: Raising the issues. Criminology & Public Policy 16(1): 73-81. Cauffman E and Steinberg L (2000) (Im)maturity of judgment in adolescence: Why adolescents may be less culpable than adults. Behavioral Sciences and the Law 18(6): 741-760. 20 Centre for Justice Innovation (2018) The voices of young adult defendants. London, UK: Centre for Justice Innovation. Cheng K K-Y and Leung B P-Y (2018) Passing the threshold of one justice system to the next: Challenges of emerging young adults in Hong Kong’s adult criminal justice process. International Journal of Offender Therapy and Comparative Criminology 62(9): 2650-2668. Cunneen C (2017) Arguments for raising the minimum age of criminal responsibility. Sydney, Australia: University of New South Wales. Deitch M, Breeden R and Weingarten R (2012) Seventeen, going on eighteen: An operational and fiscal analysis of a proposal to raise the age of juvenile jurisdiction in Texas. American Journal of Criminal Law 40(1): 1-67. Denver M (2017) Evaluating the impact of "old" criminal conviction decision guidelines on subsequent employment and arrest outcomes. Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency 54(3): 379-408. Eastwood J, Snook B and Luther K (2015) Measuring the reading complexity and oral comprehension of Canadian youth waiver forms. Crime & Delinquency 61(6): 798- 828. Ellis T and Kyo A (2017) Youth justice in Japan. In: Tonry M (ed.), Oxford handbook of crime and criminal justice online. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Farrington D P, Loeber R and Howell J C (2012) Young adult offenders: The need for more effective legislative options and justice proceedings. Criminology & Public Policy 11(4): 729-750. Farrington D P, Loeber R and Howell J C (2017) Increasing the minimum age for adult court: Is it desirable, and what are the effects? Criminology & Public Policy 16(1): 83-92. 21 Feld B C (2018) Punishing kids in juvenile and criminal courts. Crime & Justice 47(1): 417- 474. Fenwick M (2013) ‘Penal populism’ and penological change in contemporary Japan. Theoretical Criminology 17(2): 215-231. Foote D H (1992) The benevolent paternalism of Japanese criminal justice. California law review 80(2): 317-390. Forst M and Fagan J (1989) Youth in prisons and training schools: Perceptions and consequences of the treatment-custody dichotomy. Juvenile & Family Court Journal 40(1): 1-14. Fowler E and Kurlychek M C (2018) Drawing the line: Empirical recidivism results from a natural experiment raising the age of criminal responsibility. Youth Violence and Juvenile Justice 16(3): 263-278. Goldson B (2013) ‘Unsafe, unjust and harmful to wider society’: Grounds for raising the minimum age of criminal responsibility in England and Wales. Youth Justice 13(2): 111-130. Goto H (2015) Seijinnenrei no hikisage. Hogaku Kyoshitsu 423: 30-35 (in Japanese). Grisso T (1981) Juveniles' waiver of rights: Legal and psychological competence. New York, NY: Plenum Press. Grisso T, Steinberg L, Woolard J, Cauffman E, Scott E, Graham S, Lexcen F, Reppucci N D and Schwartz R (2003) Juveniles' competence to stand trial: A comparison of adolescents' and adults' capacities as trial defendants. Law and Human Behavior 27(4): 333-363. Hahn R, McGowan A, Liberman A, Crosby A, Fullilove M, Johnson R, Moscicki E, Price L, Snyder S, Tuma F, Lowy J, Briss P, Cory S and Stone G (2007) Effects on violence of laws and policies facilitating the transfer of youth from the juvenile to the adult justice 22 system: A report on recommendations of the task force on community preventive services. Morbidity and Mortality Weekly Report 56(9): 1-11. Haines K and Case S (2018) The future of youth justice. Youth Justice 18(2): 131-148. Hamai K and Ellis T (2008) Japanese criminal justice: Was reintegrative shaming a chimera? Punishment & Society 10(1): 25-46. Hebenton B and Jou S (2010) Criminology in and of China: Discipline and power. Journal of Contemporary Criminal Justice 26(1): 7-19. Henrichson C and Levshin V (2011) Cost-benefit analysis of raising the age of juvenile jurisdiction in North Carolina. New York, NY: Vera Institute of Justice. Hoffmann J L (2007) Globarization and Japanese criminal law. In: Foote D H (ed.), Law in Japan: A turning point. Seattle, WA: University of Washington Press, 334-342. Homusogokenkyujo (2007) Kenkyubuhokoku 35 - judaijihanshonen no jittai to shogu (dai 2 hokoku) -. Tokyo, Japan: Japanese Ministry of Justice. Hornby Zeller Associates (2018) The cost of raising the age of juvenile justice in Michigan: Final report: State of Michigan Legislative Council Criminal Justice Policy Commission. Hoseishingikai (2018) Shonenho・keijiho (shonennenrei・hanzaisyashogukankei)bukai dai11kaikaigi. Tokyo, Japan: Japanese Ministry of Justice (in Japanese). Illinois Juvenile Justice Commission (2013) Raising the age of juvenile court jurisdiction: The future of 17-year-olds in Illinois' justice system. Chicago, IL: Illinois Juvenile Justice Commission. Independent Democratic Conference (2016) The price of juvenile justice: Why raising the age makes cents for New York. New York, NY: Independent Democratic Conference. 23 Japan Federation of Bar Associations. (2015). Shonenho no 'seijin' nenreihikisage nikansuru ikensyo (in Japanese). Accessed 22 November, 2018, from https://www.nichibenren.or.jp/activity/document/opinion/year/2015/150220_2.html Japan Federation of Bar Associations. (2018). Shonenho niokeru 'shonen' no nenrei wo 18saimiman tosurukotoni hantaisuru ikensyo (in Japanese). Accessed 22 November, 2018, from https://www.nichibenren.or.jp/activity/document/opinion/year/2018/181121_3.html Japan Federation of Bar Associations. (2019). Shonenho no tekiyonenreihikisage ni hantaishi, shodantaito to renkeishite korenitorikumu ketugi (in Japanese). Accessed 15 June, 2019, from https://www.nichibenren.or.jp/activity/document/assembly_resolution/year/2019/2019 _2.html?fbclid=IwAR0h7E_c6979L3hb3tPz0O_DameeVYAOKfbudKnMbkJOlMlkj 6aFFoerr94 Japanese Criminal Law Scholars. (2015). Shonenho tekiyoutaisyonerei no hikisage ni hantaisuru keijihokenkyusha no seimei (in Japanese). Accessed 22 November, 2018, from https://sites.google.com/site/juvenilelaw2015/ Japanese Criminal Law Scholars. (2018). Shonen ho no jogen tonaru nenrei wo hikisagerutameno hokaisei wo okonaukotoni hantaisuru keijihokenkyusha no seimei (in Japanese). Accessed 22 November, 2018, from https://sites.google.com/view/juvenilelaw2018/%E8%A6%81%E6%97%A8?authuser =0 Japanese Ministry of Justice (2016) 'Jakunensya nitaisuru keijihosei no arikata nikansuru benkyokai': Torimatome hokokusho. Tokyo, Japan: Japanese Ministry of Justice (in Japanese). 24 Jensen E L and Metsger L K (1994) A test of the deterrent effect of legislative waiver on violent juvenile crime. Crime & Delinquency 40(1): 96-104. Justice Policy Institute (2017) Raise the age: Shifting to a safer and more effective juvenile justice system. Washington, D.C.: Justice Policy Institute. Kawade T (2015) Shonenho no tekiyonenreihikisage wo meguru giron. Keijiho Janaru 46: 3 (in Japanese). Konishi T (2013) Diversity witin an Asian country: Japanese criminal justice and criminology. In: Liu J, Hebenton B and Jou S (eds.) Handbook of asian criminology. New York, NY: Springer, 213-222. Kupchik A (2007) The correctional experiences of youth in adult and juvenile prisons. Justice Quarterly 24(2): 247-270. Kuzuno H (2005) Juvenile diversion and the get-tough movement in Japan. Ryukoku Law Review 22: 1-21. Loeber R, Hoeve M, Farrington D P, Howell J C, Slot N W and van der Laan P H (2012) Overview, conclusions, and policy and research recommendations. In: Loeber R, Hoeve M, Slot N W and van der Laan P H (eds.) Persisters and desisters in crime from adolescence into adulthood. Surrey, UK: Ashgate, 335-412. Loeffler C E and Chalfin A (2017) Estimating the crime effects of raising the age of majority: Evidence from Connecticut. Criminology & Public Policy 16(1): 45-71. Loeffler C E and Grunwald B (2015) Decriminalizing delinquency: The effect of raising the age of majority on juvenile recidivism. Journal of Legal Studies 44(2): 361-388. Loomis-Gustafson C (2017) Adjusting the bright-line age of accountability within the criminal justice system: Raising the age of majority to age 21 based on the conclusions of scientific studies regarding neurological development and culpability of young-adult offenders. Duquesne Law Review 55(1): 221-246. 25 Louisiana Youth Justice Coalition (2016) A common-sense plan for safer communities: Include 17-year-olds in juvenile court. Baton Rouge, LA: Louisiana Youth Justice Coalition. Lount S A, Hand L, Purdy S C and France A (2018) Tough talk: Youth offenders’ perceptions of communicating in the youth justice system in New Zealand. Australian & New Zealand Journal of Criminology 51(4): 593-618. Maruyama M (2017) Shonenhotekiyonenrei no hikisagehihan. Meijo Hogaku 67: 123-151 (in Japanese). Matsui S (2011) Justice for the accused or justice for victims? The protection of victims' rights in Japan. Asian-Pacific Law & Policy Journal 13(1): 54-95. McDiarmid C (2013) An age of complexity: Children and criminal responsibility in law. Youth Justice 13(2): 145-160. McGowan A, Hahn R, Liberman A, Crosby A, Fullilove M, Johnson R, Moscicki E, Price L, Snyder S, Tuma F, Lowy J, Briss P, Cory S and Stone G (2007) Effects on violence of laws and policies facilitating the transfer of juveniles from the juvenile justice system to the adult justice system. American Journal of Preventive Medicine 32(4): 7-28. Miyazawa S (2008) The politics of increasing punitiveness and the rising populism in Japanese criminal justice policy. Punishment & Society 10(1): 47-77. Modecki K L (2008) Addressing gaps in the maturity of judgment literature: Age differences and delinquency. Law and Human Behavior 32(1): 78-91. Moriya K (2018) Shonenho kaisei no rekishi to nenreihikisage. Horitsujiho 90(4): 4-9 (in Japanese). Murrie D C, Henderson C E, Vincent G M, Rockett J L and Mundt C (2009) Psychiatric symptoms among juveniles incarcerated in adult prison. Psychiatric Services 60(8): 1092-1097. 26 National Prison Rape Elimination Commission (2009) National prison rape elimination commission report. Washington D.C.: National Prison Rape Elimination Commission. Ng I Y H, Sarri R C, Shook J J and Stoffregen E (2012) Comparison of correctional services for youth incarcerated in adult and juvenile facilities in Michigan. The Prison Journal 92(4): 460-483. Ng I Y H, Shen X, Sim H, Sarri R C, Stoffregen E and Shook J J (2011) Incarcerating juveniles in adult prisons as a factor in depression. Criminal Behaviour and Mental Health 21(1): 21-34. Osaki Y (2017) Wagakuni niokeru shohensihoseido no genjo to shonenho tekiyonenrei no hikisage nikansuru kadai. Refarensu 67(10): 1-28 (in Japanese). Otsuka E (2018) Shonenhotekiyojogennenrei no hikisage: Shinken no rikai to hikosHonen no tokusei no sitenkara. Kyoiku Gabanansu Kenkyu 1: 59-66 (in Japanese). Prior D, Farrow K, Hughes N, Kelly G, Manders G, White S and Wilkinson B (2011) Maturity, young adults and criminal justice: A literature review. Birmingham, UK: Institute of Applied Social Studies, School of Social Policy, University of Birmingham. Pruin I and Dünkel F (2015) Better in Europe? European responses to young adult offending: Full report. London, UK: Barrow Cadbury Trust. Raise the Age NY. (n.d.). Accessed November 24, 2018, from http://raisetheageny.com/ Redding R E (2008) Juvenile transfer laws: An effective deterrent to delinquency? Washington D.C.: U.S. Department of Justice. Risler E A, Sweatman T and Nackerud L (1998) Evaluating the Georgia legislative waiver's effectiveness in deterring juvenile crime. Research on Social Work Practice 8(6): 657-667. 27 Ryan T (2005) Creating ‘problem kids’: Juvenile crime in Japan and revisions to the juvenile act. AnJel Journal of Japanese Law 19: 153-188. Saito T (2018) Shonenho no nenreihikisage no rekishitekisuimyaku. Kikan Keijibengo 93: 142-146 (in Japanese). Sasaki M (2016) Shonenho 'tekiyonenreihikisage' mondai to kodomo no kenrihosyo. Kodomo no Kenri Kenkyu 27: 36-46 (in Japanese). Schwarzenegger C (2003) The debate about the reform of the juvenile law in Japan. In: Foljanty-Jost G (ed.), Juvenile delinquency in Japan: Reconsidering the "crisis". Leiden, Netherlands: Brill, 173-198. Sharlein J (2018) Beyond recidivism: Investigating comparative educational and employment outcomes for adolescents in the juvenile and criminal justice systems. Crime & Delinquency 64(1): 26-52. Singer S I and McDowall D (1988) Criminalizing delinquency: The deterrent effects of the New York juvenile offender law. Law & Society Review 22(3): 521-535. Steinberg L (2008) A social neuroscience perspective on adolescent risk-taking. Developmental Review 28(1): 78-106. Steinberg L, Albert D, Cauffman E, Banich M, Graham S and Woolard J (2008) Age differences in sensation seeking and impulsivity as indexed by behavior and self- report: Evidence for a dual systems model. Developmental psychology 44(6): 1764- 1778. Steinberg L and Cauffman E (1996) Maturity of judgment in adolescence: Psychosocial factors in adolescent decision making. Law and Human Behavior 20(3): 249-272. Steiner B, Hemmens C and Bell V (2006) Legislative waiver reconsidered: General deterrent effects of statutory exclusion laws enacted post-1979. Justice Quarterly 23(1): 34-59. 28 Suzuki M and Otani A (2017) Myths of restorative features in the Japanese justice system and society: The role of apology, compensation and confession, and application of reintegrative shaming. Restorative Justice 5(2): 158-177. Suzuki M, Pai C-F and Islam M J (2018) Systematic quantitative literature review on criminological theories in Asia. Asian Journal of Criminology 3(2): 129-151. Takeuchi K (2015a) Shonenhotekiyonenrei ha hikisagerarerubekika. Jiyu to Seigi 60(10): 11- 16 (in Japanese). Takeuchi k (2015b) Shonenhotekiyonenrei no hikisage. Horitsu Jiho 87(22): 1-3 (in Japanese). Takeuchi K (2017a) Kenjiho karano kento: Shonenho no tekiyonenreihikisage no giron to 18saisenkyoken tono kankei. Hogaku Semina 744: 21-26 (in Japanese). Takeuchi K (2017b) Shonenho nichidokuhikaku: 'Tekiyonenreihikisage' nitsuite kangaeru. Sekai no Jido to Bosei 81: 64-68 (in Japanese). Takumi M (2017) Shonenho no tekiyonenrei hikisage wo meguru giron. Chosa to Joho 963: 1-14 (in Japanese). Taylor M (2015) Juvenile transfers to adult court: An examination of the long-term outcomes of transferred and non-transferred juveniles. Juvenile and Family Court Journal 66(4): 29-47. The Japanese Society of Psychiatry and Neurology. (2019). Shonenho"kaisei" nikansuru seimei (in Japanese). Accessed 15 June, 2019, from https://www.jspn.or.jp/uploads/uploads/files/activity/20190611.pdf Thomas J (2017) Raising the bar: State trends: In keeping youth out of adults courts (2015- 2017). Washington D.C.: Campaign for Youth Justice. 29 Viljoen J L, McLachlan K, Wingrove T and Penner E (2010) Defense attorneys' concerns about the competence of adolescent defendants. Behavioral Sciences and the Law 28(5): 630-646. Washington State Institute for Public Policy (2014) The effectiveness of declining juvenile court jurisdiction of youth. Washington D.C.: Washington State Institute for Public Policy. Washino K (2017) Kindaisyonenhosei niokeru miseinennenrei: Kyukeihojidai kara syowasyonenhouseitei made. Hikakuhosei Kenkyu 40: 35-69. Williams R (2015) Raising the age of juvenile court jurisdiction. LegisBrief 23(39): 1-2. Yoshida T (2003) The future of the Japanese criminal justice system. In: Walgrave L (ed.), Repositioning restorative justice. Devon, UK: Willan Publishing, 328-338. Zane S N, Welsh B C and Mears D P (2016) Juvenile transfer and the specific deterrence hypothesis: Systematic review and meta-analysis. Criminology & Public Policy 15(3): 901-925. Zelle H, Romaine C L R and Goldstein N E S (2015) Juveniles' Miranda comprehension: Understanding, appreciation, and totality of circumstances factors. Law and Human Behavior 39(3): 281-293. work_glsl52klarby5jup2536uzv3cq ---- 11211_2007_31_20_1-web 1..9 Tilburg University Justice and feelings De Cremer, D.; van den Bos, K. Published in: Social Justice Research Publication date: 2007 Document Version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): De Cremer, D., & van den Bos, K. (2007). Justice and feelings: Toward a new era in justice research. Social Justice Research, 20(1). General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal ? Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 06. apr. 2021 https://research.tilburguniversity.edu/en/publications/4cb9d618-3228-4b82-b10b-4fc91566a7ba Justice and Feelings: Toward a New Era in Justice Research David De Cremer1,3 and Kees van den Bos2 In this special issue, the relationship between feelings and justice and its con- sequences are highlighted. Five articles discuss the role that affect, feelings, and emotions play in justice processes across a variety of social settings. In the present introductory article, the position of past and present justice research in relationship to these topics is briefly reviewed. In addition, reasons are outlined to show why a focus on these issues may be pivotal for a better understanding of social justice and how this may pave the way for a new, more process-oriented era in social justice research, focusing more on ‘‘hot’’ cognitive aspects as they pertain to social justice concerns. KEY WORDS: justice; emotions; feelings; affect. Justice is essential to our social functioning as is indicated by the fact that the concept of justice (as well as its violation) often dominates our daily experiences and discussions (e.g., Finkel, 2001; Folger, 1984). Indeed, people often talk about the good and bad things they encounter in their social interactions and frame them as instances of justice versus injustice. Instances of justice take a variety of forms and researchers have throughout the last few decades devoted much attention to distinguishing among different ‘‘types’’ of justice (e.g., Bies & Moag, 1986; Greenberg & Colquitt, 2005; Thibaut & Walker, 1975). More precisely, justice involves issues of 1Department of Social Psychology, Tilburg University, P.O. Box 90153, 5000-LE Tilburg, The Netherlands. 2Utrecht University, Utrecht, The Netherlands. 3Address correspondence to: David De Cremer, Department of Social Psychology, Center of Justice and Social Decision Making, P.O. Box 90153, 5000-LE Tilburg, The Netherlands., e-mail: d.decremer@uvt.nl, www.centerofjust.com Social Justice Research, Vol. 20, No. 1, March 2007 (� 2007) DOI: 10.1007/s11211-007-0031-2 1 0885-7466/07/0300-0001/0 � 2007 Springer Science+Business Media, LLC distribution, treatment, formal and informal decision-making procedures, and so forth. This variety of justice instances has been reflected in the scientific use of concepts such as distributive, procedural, and interactional justice. Concerns about social justice go back to ancient moral philosophers like Plato and Socrates (Rawls, 1971), so by now it is no surprise that we have accumulated an impressive amount of studies addressing a variety of justice issues (for reviews, see, e.g., Brockner & Wiesenfeld, 1996; De Cremer & Tyler, 2005; Folger & Cropanzano, 1998; Greenberg & Colquitt, 2005; Miller, 1999; Tyler & Smith, 1998; Van den Bos & Lind, 2002). All these studies have shown that social justice reveals important conse- quences and that social psychological processes and factors play an important role. Indeed, the observation of justice concerns (as we encounter them in our daily experiences) has been shown to emerge also in more controlled labora- tory settings, so that we are now in a position to focus more directly on the social psychological processes that explain why people direct attention to justice and how they use information about justice (Van den Bos, 2001). As such, research on social psychology is now in a position to demonstrate that social-cognitive and motivational processes underlie the formation of justice judgments and reactions toward justice versus injustice (De Cremer & Tyler, 2005; Van den Bos & Lind, 2002). Thus, it is clear that justice matters and that people care about justice for a variety of reasons (i.e., people may even defend the view that justice is omnipresent and that the pursuit of justice is in itself a guiding and moral directive in our social lives; Montada, 2003). However, it is fair to note that by assuming that a justice motive is simply present, less attention is devoted to the initial psychological processes that determine whether people evaluate fairness or not, or, in other words, to the processes that make us understand why people evaluate instances of justice or injustice in the first place (Lerner, 2003). As noted earlier, social psychological research has shown that certain deliberative and motivational processes guide evaluations of justice, but, in our view this approach does not emphasize sufficiently that the issue of determining justice or injustice is often a matter of intuition and feeling. In making this claim, we thus agree with the view of emotion researchers that ‘‘openness to feelings is a useful and even necessary, adjunct to rationality and to effective social thinking (Damasio, 1994)’’ (Forgas, 2000, p. 1). In the present special issue, we focus our attention on the role that feelings play in the social psychology of justice. Feelings can be referred to as phenomenological states that have an affective or experiential dimension that is reflected in terms of the emotions that people feel (e.g., anger, sadness, joy, and so forth; see Watson, 2000). Thus, one specific psychological seems to have been ignored in empir- ical justice research is the role of feelings. This observation is not new, as illustrated by a rapidly growing number of quotes by justice researchers stressing the importance of emotions. For example, with respect to the status 2 Cremer and Bos of emotions in justice research, Weiss et al. (1999) argue that, ‘‘the relative lack of empirical research assessing emotional reactions to conditions of unfairness is a serious omission.’’ (p. 786,), whereas Bies and Tripp (2002) note; ‘‘to understand justice in organizations, one must understand the events that arouse the sense of injustice – the emotions of injustice’’ (pp. 204–205). Moreover, with respect to the role that emotions play, Barclay et al. (2005, p. 629) very recently observed that, ‘‘although previous justice theories and research suggest emotions are part of the relationship between the experience of injustice and the tendency to retaliate ...little empirical research has examined the mediating role of emotion.’’ Although the worries of these researchers seems to indicate that more and more attention will be directed to the emotional basis of justice, it is disappointing to see that this subject does take a central role in theoretical accounts of justice, but that currently still few attempts are undertaken to translate researchers’ conceptual thinking on justice and emotions into the practice of scientific studies. As we mentioned already, a closer focus on the relationship between emotions and justice seems warranted, particularly if one looks briefly at the history of human justice and morality. Philosophers such as Aristotle and Hume already emphasized the role that emotions play in affecting deliberative processing of justice and morality issues in our social environment (e.g., Hume, 1739/1992; Lyons, 1999). These philosophical ideas have to be seen in the perspective of the debate about whether justice and morality have a rational or a more intuitive basis (e.g., Haidt, 2001; Kant, 1959). In those days, rationalists assumed that our ability to cognitively deliberate social information differentiates us from other species and makes us superior, also in a moral way. In this process, emotions were sometimes seen as having an undesirable influence on our cognitions and way of thinking about morality and justice. Nevertheless, the discussion about the valued role of emotions continued and was also picked up in the 20th century when Adams (1965), a management researcher, introduced equity theory. In this theory, it was explicitly acknowledged that people could feel anger and resentment when being awarded in an unfair and disadavantageous manner. Around the same time, the sociologist Homans (1961) also discussed the issue of distributing outcomes and rewards and emphasized the role of anger and guilt. Despite these references to emotional influences most justice research (that was stirred very much by the work of Adams) remained a focus on attitudinal and behavioral reactions. In the 1980s and 1990s the work of Bies (1987) showed that the sense of injustice led people to experience intense emotional states that one could not easily relieve, which Folger and Cropanzano (1998) referred to as moral outrage. In the present special issue, we thus focus our attention on the role of the experience of emotions when it comes to issues of social justice. We hasten to add, however, that our promotion of a more emotional perspective 3Justice and Feelings on justice issues does not imply that cognition does not play a role. In fact, there is an abundance of evidence available in social psychology demon- strating that both cognition and affect often interact in predicting human behavior (Forgas, 2000) and justice judgments (Van den Bos, 2003). Also, evolutionary psychology sees both psychological components as interrelated as indicated by their idea that emotions are an important component of our cognitive architecture responsible for directing and guiding our actions (Cosmides & Tooby, 1992). Thus, it is not our intention to claim that cog- nition does not play a role. On the contrary, we think that more process- oriented research is needed in order to better understand how people form justice judgments (Van den Bos & Lind, 2002), and hence we would applaud a special issue on the social-cognitive aspects of justice judgment processes as well. This said, we also think it is important to simultaneously stress several reasons why a focus on emotions and feelings is also needed. First, because much justice research had (and still has) a strong focus on behavioral consequences (e.g., Brockner & Wiesenfeld, 1996), it follows logically to include a focus on emotions. That is, prior justice research has shown that negative emotions instigate actions such as protest, revenge, absenteeism, and turnover (Bies & Tripp, 2002; Griffin, O’ Leary-Kelly, & Collins, 1998; Skarlicki & Folger, 1997). This effect of emotions on behavior has also been articulated in the affective events theory (Weiss & Cropanzano, 1996) that argues that emotions can affect behavior directly (affect-driven actions) or indirectly (judgment-driven actions). Further, emotions are evaluative states although that are associated with some object, person, or event of relatively short duration (Frijda, 1993; Larsen, et al. 2002), they do have consequences for people’s actions and behaviors, referred to as action tendencies (Izard, 1993). Thus, emotions are elicited by external situations and are subjectively experienced, leading people to determine whether the emotion has a positive or negative valence, how intense the emotion is (Russell, 1980), and which discrete form the emotion takes (e.g., anger or guilt; Lerner & Keltner, 2000). Once the valence, intensity, and form of the discrete emotion are clarified, the experience is connected to a person or situation, which instigates actions (Frijda, 1993). Second, as already suggested, justice is not only a judgment but can also represent an intuition or feeling. Indeed, often people’s judgments of whe- ther a decision or treatment is fair follows from how they feel about the social instance at hand; that is, they seem to experience justice first and then make up their mind about it (see also Haidt, 2001 for a similar line of reasoning with respect to the issue of morality). In a similar vein, Chebat and Slusarczyk (2005, p. 665) recently noted that ‘‘individuals do not cal- culate justice. They rather experience a justice-related emotion and react to their emotion.’’ Thus, in line with these authors, we believe that identifying the role of emotions in justice can help us in highlighting the subjective and 4 Cremer and Bos intuitive nature of justice judgments in general and in specific situations. In fact, instances of injustice may first activate some kind of ‘‘emotional deliberation’’ before judgments, decisions, and actions are given shape. Third, as indicated earlier, discrete emotions such as anger and frus- tration are evoked by persons, situations, and other social events. The elic- itation of these discrete emotions means that they help us to appraise or evaluate the situation at hand. Indeed, Lerner, Small, and Loewenstein (2004, p. 337) note that discrete emotions elicit specific appraisals that form ‘‘an implicit lens for interpreting subsequent situations.’’ Thus, social situ- ations and events receive meaning through this appraisal process. As a result, depending on the specific emotion evoked, situations can be seen as more versus less unfair. To date, not much attention has been given to emotion- related influences on the justice judgment process (for some exceptions to this statement, see, e.g., De Cremer, 2006; Sinclair & Mark, 1991, 1992; Van den Bos, 2003). Mikula et al. (1998, p. 771) also noted that ‘‘injustice or unfairness are rarely mentioned explicitly by appraisal theorists, whereas Ellsworth and Scherer (2003) more recently have noted that an important social dimension that may elicit discrete emotions includes the evaluation of justice or equity. From this perspective, these authors suggest that justice in itself may serve as an evaluative standard or appraisal that may shape emotional reactions in terms of form, valence, and intensity. Clearly, the role of discrete emotions in the psychology of justice needs to be taken into account. It seems clear that justice researchers have to take responsibility to include emotional expressions of people’s feelings (implicit, explicit, as a dependent or independent variable and so forth) into their empirical enterprises in order to further refine and deepen our understanding of the phenomenon that we refer to as social justice. In the present special issue we brought together a series of papers that address the relationship between feelings and justice in a variety of social settings. These authors all review relevant research focusing on the emotional basis of justice and the possible consequences of this relationship. Interestingly, although our authors approach this topic from different backgrounds (social psychology, man- agement, economics, morality, and philosophy) they arrive at quite similar conclusions, namely that justice and emotions have to be seen as closely connected. The first paper by Tripp, Bies, and Aquino focuses on how emotions play a role in determining actions as a result of injustice in the workplace. According to these authors, acts of injustice can also be repaired in a positive way (i.e., related to issues of reconciliation and forgiveness) rather than in negative ways, such as taking revenge. Moreover, this paper sheds a clear view on how managers should deal with injustice and possibly vengeful acts committed in the workplace. 5Justice and Feelings The second paper, by van Winden, discusses recent research in the field of economics addressing the role of emotions in interdependent negotiation situations. In doing this, the author reviews experimental findings on the ‘‘power-to-take’’ game and focuses on how fairness is defined and approached by economists as well as which emotions (e.g., shame, guilt) play a role in negotiations. This article also provides insightful information about how economists have looked at emotions in the past and how their current perspective seems to change (thereby promoting a useful collaboration between psychology and economics; see also De Cremer et al., 2006). The third paper, by Stouten, De Cremer, and Van Dijk, focuses on the emotional and retributive implications of violations of coordination rules in symmetric public good dilemmas. The paper notes that research examining emotional and retributive reactions to violations of the equality rule by a fellow group member reveal that equality indeed is related to people’s per- sonal values and of what they consider to be fair. The paper further states that a violation of the equality rule results in emotional reactions, and these emotional experiences encourage further retributive actions. Furthermore, the authors describe the different reactions to equality violation as a func- tion of three features: (1) motives to use equality, (2) attributions for explaining the violation, and (3) the honesty of the given explanation. The fourth paper, by Opotow and McClelland, discusses hate from a variety of analytical and scientific viewpoints, including psychoanalytic, social psychological, and criminal justice literatures. Following these view- points the paper proposes a theory of hate that is interdisciplinary and spans levels of analysis. Their theoretical development has strong implications for how we may broaden our thinking about hate, and how we should study hate. The fifth paper, by Haidt and Graham, focuses on the possibility that ‘‘morality opposes justice’’ and suggests that conservatives may have moral intuitions that liberals may not recognize. More specifically, the authors note that researchers in moral psychology and social justice have agreed that morality is about matters of harm, rights, and justice. As a result of this conceptualization of morality, conservative opposition to social justice programs has appeared to be immoral and has been explained as a product of various non-moral processes. Haidt and Graham argue, however, that the moral domain is usually much broader, encompassing many more aspects of social life and valuing traditional institutions as much or more than indi- vidual liberties. The authors go on to present theoretical and empirical reasons for believing that there are in fact five psychological systems that provide the foundations for the world’s many moral codes. The five foun- dations are psychological preparations for caring about and reacting emo- tionally to harm, reciprocity (including justice, fairness, and rights), ingroup, hierarchy, and purity. According to Haidt and Graham, political liberals 6 Cremer and Bos have moral intuitions primarily based upon the first two foundations, and therefore misunderstand the moral motivations of political conservatives, who generally rely upon all five foundations. Taken together, the five articles included in this special issue on justice and feelings take different angles and very different perspectives. With this special issue we hope to have contributed to what, in addition to more process-oriented studies, is an important subject for future social justice research, namely the study of justice and feelings. ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS The preparation of this article was supported by a fellowship from the Netherlands Organization for Scientific Research (NWO) awarded to the first author (Grant No. 016-005.019) and a VICI innovational research grant from the same organization awarded to the second author (Grant No. 453.03.603). REFERENCES Adams, J. S. (1965). Inequity in social exchange. In Berkowitz, L. (ed.), Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, Vol. 2, Academic Press, New York, pp. 267–299. Barclay, L. J., Skarlicki, D. P., and Pugh, S. D. (2005). Exploring the role of emotions in injustice perceptions and retaliation. J. Appl. Psychol., 90, 629–643. Bies, R. J. (1987). The predicament of injustice: The management of moral outrage. In Cummings, L. L. and Staw, B. M. (eds.), Research in Organizational Behavior, Vol. 9, JAI Press, Greenwich, CT, pp. 289–319. Bies, R. J., and Moag, J. S. (1986). Interactional justice: Communication criteria of fairness. In Lewicki, L. R., Bazerman, M. and Sheppard, B. (eds.), Research on Negotiation in Organizations, Vol. 1, JAI Press, Greenwich, CT, pp. 43–55. Bies, R. J., and Tripp, T. M. (2002). ‘‘Hot flashes, open wounds’’: Injustice and the tyranny of its emotions. In Steiner, D. D., Skarlicki, D. P. and Gilliland, S. W. (eds.), Emerging Perspectives on Managing Organizational Justice, Information Age Publishing, Greenwich, Connecticut, pp. 203–221. Brockner, J., and Wiesenfeld, B. M. (1996). An integrative framework for explaining reactions to decisions: Interactive effects of outcomes and procedures. Psychol. Bull., 120, 189–208. Chebat, J.-C., and Slusarczyk, W. (2005). How emotions mediate the effects of perceived justice on loyalty in service recovery situations: an empirical study. J. Bus. Res., 58, 664–673. Cosmides, L., and Tooby, J. (1992). Cognitive adaptations for social exchange. In Barkow, J. H., Cosmides, L. and Tooby, J. (eds.), The adapted mind: Evolutionary psychology and the generation of culture, Oxford University Press, New York, pp. 163–228. Damasio, A. R. (1994). Descartes’ error, New York: Grosset/Putnam. De Cremer, D. (2006). Discrete emotions and procedural fairness effects on self-esteem: The role of certainty versus uncertainty-related emotions, the Netherlands: Unpublished manuscript, Tilburg University. De Cremer, D. , and Tyler, T. R. (2005). Managing group behavior: The interplay between procedural justice, sense of self, and cooperation. In Zanna, M. (ed.), Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, Vol. 37, Academic Press, New York, NY, pp. 151–218. De Cremer, D. , Zeelenberg, M., and Murnighan., J. K. (2006). Social Psychology and Economics, Mahwah, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum. 7Justice and Feelings Ellsworth, P. C., and Scherer, K. R. (2003). Appraisal processes in emotion. In Davidson, R. J., Scherer, K. R. and Goldsmith, H. H. (eds.), Handbook of Affective Sciences, Oxford University Press, New York, pp. 572–595. Finkel, N. J. (2001). Not fair! The Typology of Commonsense Unfairness, Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. Folger, R. (1984). Preface. In Folger, R. (ed.), The Sense of Injustice: Social Psychological Perspectives, Plenum, New York, pp. ix–x. Folger, R., and Cropanzano, R. (1998). Organizational Justice and Human Resource Manage- ment, Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications, Inc. Forgas, J. P. (2000). Feeling and Thinking: The Role of Affect and Social Cognition, Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Frijda, N. (1993). Moods, emotion episodes, and emotions. In Lewis, M. and Haviland, I. M. (eds.), Handbook of Emotions, Guilford Press, New York, pp. 381–403. Greenberg, J., and Colquitt, J. A. (2005). Handbook of Organizational Justice, Mahwah, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Griffin, R. W., Leary-Kelly, O’ A., and Collins, J. M. (1998). Dysfunctional Behavior in Organizations: Violent and Deviant Behavior: Part A, Stamford: JAI Press. Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychol. Bull., 108, 814–834. Homans, G. C. (1961). Social Behavior: Its Elementary Forms, New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World. Hume, D. (1739/1992). Treatise of human nature, Buffalo, Prometheus Books. Izard, C. E. (1993). Four systems for emotion activation: Cognitive and noncognitive processes. Psychol. Rev., 100, 68–90. Kant, I. (1959). Foundations of the metaphysics of morals (L. W. Beck, translation), Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs-Me. Larsen, R. J., Diener, E., and Lucas, R. E. (2002). Emotion: Models, measures, and individual differences. In Lord, R. G., Klimoski, R. J. and Kanfer, R. (eds.), Emotions In the Workplace, Jossey-Bass, San Fransisco, pp. 64–106. Lerner, M. J. (2003). The justice motive: Where social psychologists found it, how they lost it, and why they may not find it again. Pers. Soc. Psychol. Rev., 7, 388–399. Lerner, J. S., and Keltner, D. (2000). Beyond valence: Toward a model of emotion-specific influences on judgment and choice. Cognition and Emotion, 14, 473–493. Lerner, J. S., Small, D. A., and Loewenstein, G. (2004). Heart strings and purse strings: Carryover effects of emotions and economic decisions. Psychol. Sci., 15, 337–341. Lyons, W. (1999). The philosophy of cognition and emotion. In Dalgleish, T. and Pwer, M. J. (eds.), Handbook of Cognition and Emotion, John Wiley and Sons, Chichester, pp. 21–44. Mikula, G., Scherer, K. R., and Athenstaedt, U. (1998). The role of injustice in the elicitation of differential emotional reactions. Pers. Soc. Psychol. Bull., 24, 769–783. Miller, D. (1999). Principles of Social Justice, Cambridge, Massachusetts: Cambridge University Press. Montada, L. (2003). Justice, equity, and fairness in human relations. In Millon, T., Lerner, M. J. and Weiner, I. B. (eds.), Handbook of Psychology: Personality and Social Psychology, Vol. 5, John Wiley & Sons, New Jersey, pp. 537–568. Rawls, J. (1971). A Theory of Justice, Cambridge Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. Sinclair, R. C., and Mark, M. M. (1991). Mood and the endorsement of egalitarian macrojustice versus equity-based microjustice principles. Pers. Soc. Psychol. Bull., 17, 369–375. Russell, J. A. (1980). A circumplex model of affect. J. Pers. Soc Psychol., 39, 1161–1178. Sinclair, R. C., and Mark, M. M. (1992). The influence of mood state on judgment and action: Effects on persuasion, categorization, social justice, person perception, and judgmental accuracy. In Martin, L. and Tesser, A. (eds.), The Construction of Social Judgments, Erlbaum, Hillsdale, NJ, pp. 165–193. Skarlicki, D. P., and Folger, R. (1997). Retaliation in the workplace: The roles of distributive, procedural, and interactional justice. J. Appl. Psychol., 82, 434–443. Thibaut, J., and Walker, L. (1975). Procedural Justice: A psychological Analysis, Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. 8 Cremer and Bos Tyler, T. R., and Smith, H. J. (1998). Social justice and social movements. In Gilbert, D. T. and Fiske, S. T. (eds.), Handbook of Social Psychology, (4th ed. McGraw-Hill, New York, NY. Van den Bos, K (2001). Fundamental research by means of laboratory experiments is essential for a better understanding of organizational justice. J. Vocat. Behav., 58, 254–259. Van den Bos, K. (2003). On the subjective quality of social justice: The role of affect as information in the psychology of justice judgments. J. Pers. Soc. Psychol., 85, 482–498. Van den Bos, K. , and Lind, E. A. (2002). Uncertainty management by means of fairness judgments. In Zanna, M. P. (ed.), Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, Vol. 34, Academic Press, Inc, San Diego, CA, pp. 1–60. Watson, D. (2000). Mood and Temperament, New York: Guilford Press. Weiss, H. M., and Cropanzano, R. (1996). An affective events approach to job satisfaction. In Staw, B. M. and Cummings, L. L. (eds.), Research in Organizational Behavior, Vol. 18, JAI Press, Greenwich, CT, pp. 1–47. Weiss, H. M., Suckow, K., and Cropanzano, R. (1999). Effects of justice conditions on discrete emotions. J. Appl. Psychol., 84, 786–794. 9Justice and Feelings << /ASCII85EncodePages false /AllowTransparency false /AutoPositionEPSFiles true /AutoRotatePages /None /Binding /Left /CalGrayProfile (None) /CalRGBProfile (sRGB IEC61966-2.1) /CalCMYKProfile (ISO Coated) /sRGBProfile (sRGB IEC61966-2.1) /CannotEmbedFontPolicy /Error /CompatibilityLevel 1.3 /CompressObjects /Off /CompressPages true /ConvertImagesToIndexed true /PassThroughJPEGImages true /CreateJDFFile false /CreateJobTicket false /DefaultRenderingIntent /Perceptual /DetectBlends true /ColorConversionStrategy /sRGB /DoThumbnails true /EmbedAllFonts true /EmbedJobOptions true /DSCReportingLevel 0 /SyntheticBoldness 1.00 /EmitDSCWarnings false /EndPage -1 /ImageMemory 524288 /LockDistillerParams true /MaxSubsetPct 100 /Optimize true /OPM 1 /ParseDSCComments true /ParseDSCCommentsForDocInfo true /PreserveCopyPage true /PreserveEPSInfo true /PreserveHalftoneInfo false /PreserveOPIComments false /PreserveOverprintSettings true /StartPage 1 /SubsetFonts false /TransferFunctionInfo /Apply /UCRandBGInfo /Preserve /UsePrologue false /ColorSettingsFile () /AlwaysEmbed [ true ] /NeverEmbed [ true ] /AntiAliasColorImages false /DownsampleColorImages true /ColorImageDownsampleType /Bicubic /ColorImageResolution 150 /ColorImageDepth -1 /ColorImageDownsampleThreshold 1.50000 /EncodeColorImages true /ColorImageFilter /DCTEncode /AutoFilterColorImages false /ColorImageAutoFilterStrategy /JPEG /ColorACSImageDict << /QFactor 0.76 /HSamples [2 1 1 2] /VSamples [2 1 1 2] >> /ColorImageDict << /QFactor 0.76 /HSamples [2 1 1 2] /VSamples [2 1 1 2] >> /JPEG2000ColorACSImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 30 >> /JPEG2000ColorImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 30 >> /AntiAliasGrayImages false /DownsampleGrayImages true /GrayImageDownsampleType /Bicubic /GrayImageResolution 150 /GrayImageDepth -1 /GrayImageDownsampleThreshold 1.50000 /EncodeGrayImages true /GrayImageFilter /DCTEncode /AutoFilterGrayImages true /GrayImageAutoFilterStrategy /JPEG /GrayACSImageDict << /QFactor 0.76 /HSamples [2 1 1 2] /VSamples [2 1 1 2] >> /GrayImageDict << /QFactor 0.15 /HSamples [1 1 1 1] /VSamples [1 1 1 1] >> /JPEG2000GrayACSImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 30 >> /JPEG2000GrayImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 30 >> /AntiAliasMonoImages false /DownsampleMonoImages true /MonoImageDownsampleType /Bicubic /MonoImageResolution 600 /MonoImageDepth -1 /MonoImageDownsampleThreshold 1.50000 /EncodeMonoImages true /MonoImageFilter /CCITTFaxEncode /MonoImageDict << /K -1 >> /AllowPSXObjects false /PDFX1aCheck false /PDFX3Check false /PDFXCompliantPDFOnly false /PDFXNoTrimBoxError true /PDFXTrimBoxToMediaBoxOffset [ 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 ] /PDFXSetBleedBoxToMediaBox true /PDFXBleedBoxToTrimBoxOffset [ 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 ] /PDFXOutputIntentProfile (None) /PDFXOutputCondition () /PDFXRegistryName (http://www.color.org?) /PDFXTrapped /False /Description << /DEU /ENU >> >> setdistillerparams << /HWResolution [2400 2400] /PageSize [2834.646 2834.646] >> setpagedevice work_glyzbc26nfcrhfj5sadyatfuhi ---- Criminal Justice In Malawi JOURNAL OF AFRICAN LAW Vol. XI Autumn 1967 No. 3 NOTES AND NEWS CRIMINAL JUSTICE IN MALAWI Introduction On the last day of October, 1966, the President of the Republic of Malawi, Dr. H. Kamuzu Banda, appointed a Commission to enquire into criminal justice in Malawi. The Commission was asked to enquire into the existing practice, procedure and rules of evidence followed both in the High Court and under local customary law. Recommendations were asked for so as to simplify practice, procedure and the rules of evidence in the courts of Malawi with a view to achieving a more expeditious, efficient and uniform administration of justice, without undue regard to techni- calities. The Commission was also invited to make such other recommendations for the better administration ofjustice as it thought desirable. The terms of reference in each case confined the Commis- sion to the field of criminal justice. The President appointed a very strong, experienced and distin- guished Commission. The Chiefjustice was Chairman, and the other members were the Attorney-General, the leader of the Nominated Members of Parliament (who is also the Chairman of the Malawi Law Society), three Chiefs, one from each of the three Regions of the country, and the Chairman of the Blantyre Local Court. The Commission completed its enquiries and submitted its report to the President within four months of being appointed. During the early part of this period the three Chiefs and the Chairman of the Blantyre Local Court toured the country and prepared an exposition of customary law relating to criminal matters. The President's instructions to this Committee were "that they should go all over the country and find out from the people the way things were done in the old days and at the same time how things are done now, and compare the two". The Report of the Presidential Commission was laid before Parliament1 and a motion to accept it was unanimously carried on April 3rd, 1967.2 The substance of the Report may conveniently be divided into four parts: the investigation and prosecution of cases, the courts of justice, procedure and evidence, and miscellaneous recommendations. 1 Report of the Presidential Commission on Criminal Justice, February, 1967. 1 Hansard, Malawi Parliament, Fourth Session, Fourth Meeting. April 3rd, 1967. 147 https://doi.org/10.1017/S0021855300005064 Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:34, subject to the https://doi.org/10.1017/S0021855300005064 https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://www.cambridge.org/core 148 Notes and News [ig67]J.A.L. The Investigation and Prosecution of Gases The Commission recognised that a shortage of police officers sufficiently trained and experienced in criminal investigation and in prosecution was leading to delay and to defective and incomplete investigation. Magistrates complained of the inexperience of some police officers in presenting evidence and in knowing which points to emphasise and which to ignore. The Commission therefore recommended the appointment of a suitably qualified Criminal Investigation Department Training Officer, and the setting up of a specialised Fraud Squad within the C.I.D., with a director, an accountant and supporting staff. They also recommended the securing of the services of an officer qualified to speak as an expert in both ballistics and hand-writing, and of a police surgeon so as to reduce calls on the time of other medical officers. To avoid the dangers of loss of capable officers because promotion appointments lie only within the general promotion structure of the police force, the Commission recommended that a special Prosecu- tion Branch be established within the police force with its own promotion structure. The Director of Public Prosecutions is to organise training courses for police officers serving within the Prosecution Branch. These officers are to serve a pupillage in the Director of Public Prosecutions' department, and are, wherever practicable, to have direct access to state counsel. The Report emphasised the need to avoid delay in bringing cases to trial, the need to recruit from outside Malawi counsel with adequate experience, and the need to continue the training of local state counsel after they have been appointed. Comment was also made on the fact that the courts "were leaning over backwards so that there should be no suggestion that they were being unduly hard on junior counsel", and the courts, especially the High Court, are encouraged to be at pains to point out errors and defects in the presentation of cases by legal practitioners. It was particularly emphasised that once a point in the prosecution's case has been sufficiently covered, no useful purpose is served by calling additional evidence to testify further to it. The Courts of Justice (a) The High Court.—With a view to avoiding delay in the admini- stration of criminal justice, the Report recommended that a Division of the High Court be established in the Central Region, at Lilongwe, the site of the proposed new capital of Malawi, and that fixed assizes should be held at Blantyre, Lilongwe, and in the Northern Region. The Commission considered that judgments in the High Court should be re-served only in exceptional cases, and that normally judgment should be pronounced immediately at the conclusion of the hearing; that judgments of the Supreme Court of Appeal should be embodied in a single majority judgment, dissenting judgments not being recorded; that appeal from a revision order or from a summary dismissal of a first appeal should be only by leave of the https://doi.org/10.1017/S0021855300005064 Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:34, subject to the https://doi.org/10.1017/S0021855300005064 https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://www.cambridge.org/core Vol. I I . No. 3 Notes and News 149 High Court or the Supreme Court of Appeal; and that every effort should be made to expedite the hearing of appeals in capital cases. It was emphasised that a conviction ought not to be set aside on appeal unless the Court of Appeal is satisfied that, irrespective of technical defects or omissions, the appellant was wrongly convicted; when a conviction is set aside the Appeal Court must in all cases consider whether a new trial should be ordered. While realising that not all fraud cases can be dealt with by the High Court, the Commission recommended that all those of serious complexity should be prosecuted by state counsel and tried by the High Court. (b) The Magistrates' Courts.—In the Magistrates' Courts the Commis- sion recommended that vacancies in the establishment of Resident Magistrates be filled as quickly as possible and that only those with adequate experience of magisterial work be appointed. It was felt that local officers should have a practical grounding in the work of Local Courts, in prosecuting and defending in the Magistrates' Courts and in the High Court, before being appointed as Resident Magistrates. The Senior Resident Magistrate is to be relieved of much of his court work in order to supervise the work of other magistrates. Magistrates and Local Court chairmen are reminded of the virtues of punctuality in attendance in court. (c) The Local Courts.—Having studied the exposition of customary law prepared by some of its members, the Commission concluded that defilement, indecent assault, and rape are matters which lie peculiarly within the scope of local law and custom, and that the jurisdiction of the Local Courts in these matters should be extended. The possibility of a remand for sentence in more serious cases to a superior court could be considered. (d) Other courts.—-In order to relieve other courts of the routine work of dealing with small debts and minor traffic offences so that Magistrates and Local Court chairmen may give their time to the trial of more serious offences, it was suggested that a new Small Debts Court and a new Traffic Court be established by the City Council of Blantyre, the largest urban centre in the country. Procedure and Evidence Guided by the overriding principle that substantial justice should be done without undue regard to technicalities, the Commission recommended the redrafting and simplification of the Criminal Procedure Code, and particular reference was made to the view that Local Courts should be empowered to dispense with cross-examina- tion by parties when no legal practitioner appears, but that the Local Court chairmen themselves should carry out the requisite examination. It was also suggested that the accused, on a case to answer being found, should be a compellable witness required to give an account of his conduct and to answer relevant questions put to him by the court, complainant or prosecutor. Another suggestion was that magistrates https://doi.org/10.1017/S0021855300005064 Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:34, subject to the https://doi.org/10.1017/S0021855300005064 https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://www.cambridge.org/core 150 Notes and News [1967] J.A.L. should not be required to record reasons for their verdicts in minor cases. A major recommendation was that a short code setting out the rules of evidence in criminal cases should be drafted, providing that the admissibility of extra-judicial confessions shall be part of the general issue; that formal admissions by an accused person in court of facts in issue shall be permitted in criminal cases; and that documentary reports of medical officers purporting on the face of them to be authentic shall be admitted in evidence in all cases in which their contents are not in dispute. Miscellaneous Recommendations A number of miscellaneous observations and recommendations were made in the Report. In dealing with prisons it was felt that the standard of subsistence provided in the prisons should be made reasonably to accord with the general measure of subsistence prevailing in the country. It was also recommended that the quantum and hours of work being performed by hard-labour prisoners should be reviewed so as to avoid prisoners being treated with undue leniency. The Commission advised that no account of periods spent in prison awaiting trial should be taken into account in assessing sentence unless remand prisoners opted for hard labour, remand prisoners to have the right so to opt. It was recommended that District Commissioners and Local Court Commissioners should join chairmen and members of Local Courts, magistrates and judges as prison visitors, but that only complaints from convicted prisoners should be heard; judges should not hear complaints from appellants whose appeal to the High Court or Supreme Court of Appeal are still pending. The Commission recommended the introduction of legal educa- tion in the University of Malawi so as to make possible effective research into local law, practice and procedure, and so as to enable Malawians to qualify in the law inside Malawi. The Commission was made aware of a dissatisfaction with the normal measure of sentence in manslaughter cases, and advised, in order to ascertain, as is desirable, the feelings of the deceased person's community in this matter, that before awarding sentence judges should seek the opinion of assessors as to the appropriate measure of sentence. Under local law and custom in Malawi the question of compensa- tion in homicide cases is of prime importance, and the Commission was of the opinion that Local Courts are the tribunals most suited to adjudicate on this matter, and that in each case of homicide the Registrar of the High Court should bring the case to the notice of the District Commissioner in whose district the family of the deceased person lives, with a view to the District Commissioner investigating the circumstances and advising as to the seeking of compensation through the Local Court. Conclusion It is clear from the Report of the Commission, and from state- ments made in Parliament, that there have been undoubted delays https://doi.org/10.1017/S0021855300005064 Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:34, subject to the https://doi.org/10.1017/S0021855300005064 https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://www.cambridge.org/core Vol. I I . No. 3 Notes and News 151 and defects in the investigation, prosecution and trial of criminal cases in Malawi, and that these delays and defects were causing widespread dissatisfaction in the country. This dissatisfaction is not attributed to a single cause, but is the result of a combination of circumstances, particularly those stem- ming from a shortage of appropriately qualified and experienced personnel, and those resulting from a "spate of technicalities" which "proliferated out of all sense of proportion". The shortage of staff led to a failure of proper cooperation between the courts, counsel and police, and the position was one of "everybody in the court at the time all learning together". Behind all the recommendations made, the Commission empha- sised "the need for a sound legal and judicial system, and a magis- tracy and judiciary that command respect and confidence", the need for a "system of criminal justice as simple and uncomplicated as possible, directed at enforcing the criminal law against guilty persons speedily and decisively, without unnecessary regard for technicalities". The recommendations were made to achieve this, "that the guilty shall be convicted speedily and properly punished (and) . . . the innocent shall be set free and that they shall also be set free quickly". COLIN BAKER1 T H E AFRICAN LAW REPORTS A new law-reporting organisation has been established for the countries of English-speaking Africa. The African Law Reports will operate under an editorial grant from the Ford Foundation, adminis- tered by the Sailer Project of the International Legal Center, New York, and will be published by Oceana Publications Inc., Dobbs Ferry, N.Y. The organisation is under the direction of Dr. Alan Milner, Fellow of Trinity College, Oxford and formerly the Dean of the Faculty of Law, Ahmadu Bello University, Zaria, Nigeria. The Existing Law Reporting Systems Although law reports are one of the basic tools of any common law system, many of the common law jurisdictions of Africa suffer the disadvantage of inadequate law reporting. With the exception of commercially operated series in East, South and until recently Central Africa, African law reports have normally been published under the aegis of individual colonial or independent governments. Almost without exception, they have been highly selective in their coverage, of variable editorial quality, and sporadic in their publication. At an early stage of colonial rule, the British government sponsored the publication of individual series of reports for many of its African territories. Some ended almost before they began, as in the case of the old Sierra Leone reports (1912-1924, 1 volume); others filled only a few slender volumes over several decades (e.g. Northern Rhodesia 1931-1954, 5 volumes; Nyasaland 1922-1952, 6 volumes; Zanzibar 1 Principal, Institute of Public Administration, University of Malawi. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0021855300005064 Cambridge Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:34, subject to the https://doi.org/10.1017/S0021855300005064 https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://www.cambridge.org/core work_gmpgosgdvjanrm3qa33pey7kuy ---- EVIDENCE BASED PUBLIC HEALTH POLICY AND PRACTICE Evidence based health promotion: recollections, reflections, and reconsiderations K C Tang, J P Ehsani, D V McQueen . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . J Epidemiol Community Health 2003;57:841–843 I mproving the evidence base of health promotion is high on the agenda of the international health promotion commu- nity and it is becoming increasingly apparent that evidence is needed by practitioners for effective health promotion interventions. It is generally accepted that with quality findings from intervention studies, practitioners can make better decisions to achieve effectiveness in their interven- tions. Moreover, without evidence of effective health promo- tion, it may be difficult to obtain policy support. Over the past few years, the debate on the concept or nature of evidence in health promotion effectiveness and its appraisal has focused on the design of a study and other related methodological issues such as validity of indicators, efficacy of the intervention, and context in which the intervention operates.1–4 To a great extent the quality of the evidence has been determined by using the hierarchical structure established by those working in evidence based medicine5 adopting a positivist paradigm. THE RULES OF THE NATURAL SCIENCES To this end, emphasis has been placed on achieving the three rules of scientific inquiry: predictability, repeatability, and falsifiability, when determining the strength of evidence. These are based on widely recognised principles stemming from discussions in the philosophy of science. Predictability is said to be met when a properly implemented intervention will bring about an expected outcome, given that the key elements of the intervention and the cause-effect interaction among those elements are known. The elements of the intervention and the causal relations of those elements thus need to be specified. Repeatability, sometimes referred to as replicability, refers to universal application of the interven- tion, regardless of time and place. The intervention is therefore required to yield the same result wherever and whenever it is carried out. To be falsifiable, the intervention must be capable of being disproved as an effective interven- tion. Once implemented, the intervention is validated if rigorous evaluation research demonstrates that it works and is falsified if it is shown to be ineffective or harmful. Health promotion operates in an environment where numerous cultural, social, economic, and political factors interact. Given a complex context where the links among the elements of an intervention are interrelated, causality, more often than not, cannot be directly established. It is indeed difficult to define causality in a succinct manner.6 7 In brief, it refers to, in biomedical sciences, a probabilistic notion that if an ‘‘x’’ (the exposure) precedes a ‘‘y’’ (the effect) and there is a statistical association between ‘‘x’’ and ‘‘y’’ and if a reduction of ‘‘x’’ will lead to a reduction of ‘‘y’’ and there is not a ‘‘z’’ confounding the association, then causation is imputed. Repeatability of an intervention, regardless of time and place, also has proved difficult to be achieved. The application of the rules of science to health promotion is therefore of questionable merit. It is also important to note that a large part of health promotion is of a social science nature. Behavioural and policy changes are two key focal concerns of many health promotion activities and behaviour is structured by society or is socially constructed. Behaviour here refers to that of individuals as well as of organisations and as such can include lifestyle practices and participation among people in the wider community, sales promotion behaviour of the private industries, and the predisposition of policy makers. Taking into consideration the various types of behaviour (or vested interests), the expressed needs of people in the wider community and the availability of resources, intervention activities as well as policy decisions are determined. When behaviour of individuals, organisations, or the political process is the focus, whether it relates to lifestyle practices, sales decisions or public policy formulation, the explanatory power of science will be limited. Above all, it may be problematic to fit these rules of the natural sciences to the social science disciplines.8 Although the finding of an intervention study may not constitute scientific fact as described by the criteria above, it can be a piece of evidence in the sense that it is a fact disclosed as a result of an evaluation process whereby methods of reasonable rigour are used. In health promotion, for an intervention to be effective, a combination of behavioural, social, and environmental strategies is used. For such interventions, it is not uncommon that the ‘‘what works’’ component is known but ‘‘how it works’’ component remains unclear. This allowance does not imply a compro- mise of accepted standards of methodological rigour in the development, implementation and evaluation of interven- tions. Rather, it expands the range and scope of what can be regarded as valid ‘‘evidence’’ and hence broadens the knowledge and experience base that practitioners and policy makers can draw from. TOWARDS AN IDEAL TYPOLOGY OF EVIDENCE One type of evidence can be found without meeting the causality criterion but where the different elements of an intervention work as a whole to produce the desired outcome. Interventions that may have limited repeatability—for example, only at the local level and within a certain period—can be classified as another type of evidence so long as the intervention works. In sum, a typology of evidence emerges, consisting of four classifications (table 1). A. Evidence of implemented interventions that meet the criteria for scientific fact—that is, they are proved predict- able, and repeatable, regardless of time and place. Assuming there is compliance, immunisation and condom use are classic examples of intervention where the elements of the intervention are known, the cause effect interaction is apparent and have universal application. B. Evidence from interventions that produce desired outcomes and are predictable but are repeatable only at a local level within a certain period of time. The development of 841 www.jech.com o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://je ch .b m j.co m / J E p id e m io l C o m m u n ity H e a lth : first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /je ch .5 7 .1 1 .8 4 3 o n 4 N o ve m b e r 2 0 0 3 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://jech.bmj.com/ assertiveness skills in commercial sex workers to encourage clients to use condoms, coupled with the availability of condoms, is an example of such an intervention where the cause-effect relation can be determined and the elements readily identified. However, the applicability of this inter- vention is limited to settings where the selling of sex is culturally acceptable and not otherwise. C. Evidence from interventions that work as predicted to produce desired outcomes, without meeting the causality criterion, and are repeatable at any time and anywhere. Acupuncture is an example for treating some illness conditions such as pain relief. D. Evidence from interventions that work as predicted, without meeting the causality criterion, and are repeatable only at a local level within a certain period of time. Community based trials to promote physical activity use a combination of behavioural, social, and environmental action areas which are effective, however which specific component of the action areas led to the outcome is unknown. The success may also be attributable to the interaction effect of the different types of action areas at work. Furthermore, the application is limited by the context where the intervention is applied; hence universal application cannot be achieved. STRENGTH AND TYPES OF EVIDENCE Thus far, the strength or hierarchy of evidence of an inter- vention is, in essence, determined by its evaluation design taking into consideration other methodological issues such as indicator validity and intervention efficacy. Yet the strength of a piece of evidence derived from an intervention may not be simply determined by evaluation design and related metho- dological issues. They are necessary but not sufficient. As illustrated above, there are four types of evidence and with- in each type, all the above mentioned methodological issues apply. Yet implicit in the typology, the strength of evidence of type A would seem to be superior to that of other types. Even if an intervention is shown to work and the methods used to evaluate that intervention are sound, there are other dimensions that need to be certain, for example, how it works and whether or not it is repeatable. The typology presented expands the dimension of evidence for health promotion interventions in the way that the typology presents a horizontal axis for the appraisal of evidence, opening new dimensions for practice and policy formulation and research. KNOWLEDGE BASED HEALTH PROMOTION For improving the evidence base of health promotion, in addition to the deliberation on the typology of evidence, there are other key concerns. In practice, it is important to note that evidence alone cannot constitute effective practice, as is the case of evidence based medicine.9 As suggested, external evidence can inform, but can never replace, the expertise of individual practitioners. It is this expertise that decides whether the external evidence is applied to the target group of an intervention at all and if so, how it should be used for achieving effectiveness. In other words, for an effective intervention, other critical areas in addition to evidence need to be taken into consideration—for example, the needs and expectations of direct service recipients, the interests of other key stakeholders, and the competency of a practitioner in planning and evaluation. Conscientious and judicious use of evidence is only one competency element of health promotion. It is necessary but not sufficient for achieving effective health promotion. Health promotion practitioners are required to be able to absorb and use knowledge in many competency areas as specified in a review report.10 In policy formulation, while the strength of evidence is a base for policy development, there are also other considerations, for example, the socio-political and fiscal climate within which governments and organisations operate as well as the vested interests. The introduction of the typology will also give policy makers another dimension for consideration. In research, effective health promotion often uses a combination of behavioural, social, and environmental strategies that work in synergy. The relation between the outcome variables and predictor variables are complex and not linear. The causal-effect relations of these variables cannot be addressed by traditional quantitative methods in public health alone. This necessitates new modes of practice to emerge and research methods in social sciences to be used, for example, the use of structured equation modelling to examine the validity of theoretical constructs and establish causal effects. The use of qualitative methods will help acquire a better understanding of the meaning of a concept and dissect the complexity of interactions. The use of qualitative methods may also be useful for achieving generalisability or transferability using the notion of repre- sentativeness in the concept when representativeness in the sample cannot be achieved.11 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS The authors wish to thank Dr Pekka Puska, Director, Department of Non-Communicable Disease Prevention and Health Promotion, World Health Organisation, for his comments on an earlier draft of the manuscript. Table 1 The four classifications used in typology of evidence A B C D What works: elements of an intervention that work (intervention demonstrated to work in evaluation research) What works is What works is What works is What works is Known Known Known Known How it works: cause-effect interaction among those elements (the components and how they work) How it works is How it works is How it works is How it works is Known Known Not known Not known Repeatability Repeatability is Repeatability is Repeatability is Repeatability is Universal Limited Universal Limited 842 Tang, Ehsani, McQueen www.jech.com o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://je ch .b m j.co m / J E p id e m io l C o m m u n ity H e a lth : first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /je ch .5 7 .1 1 .8 4 3 o n 4 N o ve m b e r 2 0 0 3 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://jech.bmj.com/ Authors’ affiliations . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . K C Tang, J P Ehsani, National and Community Programmes, Department of Non-Communicable Disease prevention and Health Promotion, WHO, Geneva D V McQueen, National Center for Chronic Disease Prevention and Health Promotion, CDC, USA Correspondence to: Dr K C Tang, National and Community Programmes, Department of Non-communicable Disease Prevention and Health Promotion, World Health Organisation, 20 Avenue Appia, CH- 1211 Geneva 27, Switzerland; tangkc@who.int Accepted for publication 5 August 2003 REFERENCES 1 Raphael D. The question of evidence in health promotion. Health Promotion International 2000;15:355–67. 2 McQueen D. Strengthening the evidence base for health promotion. Health Promotion International 2001;16:261–8. 3 McQueen D. The evidence debate. J Epidemiol Community Health 2002;56:83–4. 4 Rychetnik L, Frommer M, Hawe P, et al. Criteria for evaluating evidence on public health interventions. J Epidemiol Community Health 2002;56:119–27. 5 Centre for Evidence-Based Medicine. Levels of evidence. http:// cebm.Jr2.ox.ac.uk/docs/levels.html (accessed Oct 2002). 6 Hill B. The environment and disease: association or causation? Proc R Soc Med 1965;58:295–300. 7 Ehring D. Causation and persistence: a theory of causation. New York: Oxford University Press, 1997. 8 McQueen D. Perspectives on health promotion: theory, evidence, practice and the emergence of complexity. Health Promotion International 2000;15:95–7. 9 Sackett D, Rosenberg W, Gray J, et al. Evidenced-based medicine: What it is and what it isn’t. BMJ 1996;312:71–2. 10 WHO SEARO. Review of certified education and training programmes for health promotion and education in the South East Asia region. New Delhi: WHO SEARO, 2002. 11 Strauss A, Corbin J. Basics of qualitative research: grounded theory procedures and techniques. California: Sage, 1990. THE JECH GALLERY . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . Influential women in occupational health Victoire Cappe—for social justice 1886–1927 Country of birth: Belgium V ictoire Cappe taught social justice as a leader in the Christian Democratic labour movement. She was one of the founders of the Catholic school for social work. In 1907, Cappe founded the Syndicat de l’Aiguille, the first union for needleworkers, dressmakers, and seamstresses. 1 She also began study circles (monthly meetings for young girls and women) to overcome ignorance and indifference, and reach autonomy of mind and action. Facing resistance from most of the clergy, but with the support of Cardinal Mercier, Cappe expanded unions to Brussels, then other Belgian cities. Later, she founded a national Christian professional women’s union. Although suffering with depression, she wrote a book (La Femme Belge), and edited monthly reviews, including a new journal, Joie et Travail. Cappe attended the first Congress of the International Labor Organization in 1919 in Washington, DC, and the first international congress for women workers preceeding it. With Maria Baers and Isidore Maus, Cappe created the International Catholic Union of Social Work. D F Salerno Clinical Communications Scientist, Pfizer Global Research and Development–Ann Arbor Laboratories, Ann Arbor, MI, USA I L Feitshans Adjunct Faculty, Cornell University, School of Industrial and Labor Relations, Albany, NY, USA Correspondence to: Deborah F Salerno, 2800 Plymouth Road, Ann Arbor, MI, USA; deborah.salerno@pfizer.com REFERENCE 1 Keymolen D. Victoire Cappe 1886–1927. Une vie chrétienne, sociale, féministe, Leuven, Belgium: Presses Universitaires de Louvain, 2001. (photo courtesy of Leuven KADOC—Katholiek Documentatie, Katholieke Universiteit) ‘‘…respect for the rights of working women and elevation of their dignity.’’ Evidence based health promotion 843 www.jech.com o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://je ch .b m j.co m / J E p id e m io l C o m m u n ity H e a lth : first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /je ch .5 7 .1 1 .8 4 3 o n 4 N o ve m b e r 2 0 0 3 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://jech.bmj.com/ work_gnbsscd7o5byzjetqhq2rsdnle ---- Review Spaces of environmental justice Ryan Holifield, Michael Porter and Gordon Walker (Eds.) Wiley-Blackwell, Malden, MA, 2010, viii+263pp., ISBN: 978-1444332452 Contemporary Political Theory (2015) 14, e45–e47. doi:10.1057/cpt.2015.7; published online 17 February 2015 Until the mid-1990s, ‘environmental (in)justice’ was conceived largely in terms of the racialized distribution of environmental ‘bads,’ usually in the United States. Environmental justice (hereafter EJ) research largely consisted of rigorous empirical studies demonstrating that racial minorities in the United States were disproportio- nately exposed to environmental hazards. This research not only led to important debates about the racialization of ‘environmentalism’, but also to policy action, including President Clinton’s 1994 signing of Executive Order 12 898 (‘Federal Actions to Address Environmental Justice in Minority Populations and Low-Income Populations’). The field has evolved considerably since the mid-1990s, as the editors of this collection map out in their introduction. First, scholars and activists outside of the United States have been pushed to consider whether or how EJ might be applied in different national contexts. Second, and perhaps of even greater significance for readers of this journal, those earlier studies’ limited theoretical depth and engagement was increasingly seen as a liability. David Schlosberg’s seminal work emphasized the need to conceptualize EJ in terms of participation and recognition, as well as distribution, and also that ‘doing justice’ includes allowing the subjects of (in)justice to define justice for themselves. The limits of traditional policy interventions also may have helped to clarify the ways in which such key concepts as ‘space’, ‘race’, ‘justice’ and ‘politics’ need to be theorized more carefully. Spaces of Environmental Justice thus refers to bringing the concepts of EJ to new geographic locations, and to placing EJ into new theoretical contexts and conversations. After the editors’ introduction, the book is divided into two parts, each with four chapters. In Part 1, ‘Frameworks for Critical Environmental Justice Research,’ contributors argue for opening up new ways of thinking about and conducting EJ research. Gordon Walker’s first chapter provides a nice opening, laying out the connections between critical geography’s more complex theorizations of space (‘constructed by and through social practices’ (p. 25)) and Schlosberg’s development of the idea of EJ as ‘trivalent, integrating questions of distribution with those of © 2015 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Vol. 14, 4, e45–e47 www.palgrave-journals.com/cpt/ http://dx.doi.org/10.1057/cpt.2015.7 http://www.palgrave-journals.com/cpt recognition’ (p. 35). Ryan Holifield then contrasts urban political ecology, which has become a significant theoretical framework in EJ research, with more recent attempts to use Actor-Network Theory in an EJ context. Holifield argues provocatively against a theoretical synthesis of these two approaches, as each asks different questions and thus illuminates different aspects of EJ. Susan Buckingham and Rakibe Kulcur’s chapter focuses on questions of gender. Despite the fact that women have led many EJ movements (p. 73), they argue that gender analysis has been conspicuously absent from EJ research. Part of the case for this is built on an analysis of the gender composition of major European environmental organizations. And while male domination of these organizations may have significant consequences for broader public understandings of ‘environmental justice,’ this is not to say that grassroots EJ organizations or movements are gendered in the same way. More persuasively, they also point to the relative inattention paid to the scales of the household and the body, where the burdens of responsibility fall disproportionately on women. Hilda Kurtz’s chapter draws on theories of the racial state, to argue that even though EJ activists often look to the state for protection against environmental injustice (as in Executive Order 12 898), the state itself plays a significant role in ‘shaping racialized patterns of spatial injustice’ (p. 97). Part 2, ‘Spaces for Critical Environmental Justice Research’, turns to more geographically specific case studies. Petra Tschakert’s chapter discusses her work with artisanal gold miners in Ghana, illuminating the complex politics of scale involved in mining in the global south. Both local labour and host states are significantly disadvantaged vis-à-vis multinational mining corporations. At the same time, Ghanaian ‘artisanal’ miners, who comprise a majority of the mining labour force, operate outside of the formal economy, and often without legal protection or recognition. Tschakert’s participatory research methods show the importance of focusing on inequities of recognition and participation, but also the ways that highly engaged local research may appear problematic at larger scales: ‘galamsey [artisanal] miners did not envision any radical changes themselves …. The large majority … wished to be employed by one of the large mining companies’ (pp. 135, 138). The call for legal (state) recognition of artisanal miners also lies in tension with the understanding of the state developed in Kurtz’s chapter. Zoe Meletis and Lisa Campbell innovatively apply an EJ frame to an ecotourism site in Costa Rica. That site’s ‘isolation’ is an important part of its ecotourist appeal: ‘with no access by road and no cars in town … [it] seems more “natural” ’ (p. 170). At the same time, this ‘isolation,’ contributes to a significant problem in dealing with solid waste. Recalling that ecotourism sites are in fact ‘produced’, not ‘natural’, underlines the power imbalances, and hence EJ issues, at play. Karen Bickerstaff and Julian Agyeman’s chapter on a conflict over shipbreaking in northeast England focuses on the politics of shifting scale-frames. Perhaps because the identity politics that is so central to US EJ struggles is less entrenched in England, and perhaps because this particular struggle involved an international NGO involved in a local campaign, there is greater Review e46 © 2015 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Vol. 14, 4, e45–e47 political room for manoeuvre on both sides. The final chapter, by Julie Sze et al., examines a policy-making process for managing the Sacramento-San Joaquin Delta in California’s Central Valley. Here, too, ‘the conflict over scale [is] at the core of the politics’ (p. 221). How is ‘the Delta’ defined and represented? Who is and is not afforded representation in the processes that manage the Delta? In a classic move of EJ analysis, the authors note that ‘local interests are constructed as parochial, short sighted, and irrational, whereas advocates for the state are considered to be acting for the abstract good, rather than in the service of capital and large water users (agriculture and urban water districts)’ (p. 238). While each of the individual chapters provides interesting insights, a firmer editorial hand might have helped the book as a whole to initiate a fuller dialogue about the development of the field. Outside of the editors’ introduction, there are very few references made by the authors to other chapters in the book, despite obvious opportunities to do so. More generally, the chapters each seek to push EJ research in new, and different, directions. The result is that occasionally terrain that is deplored as conventional and inadequate in one chapter is what is covered in another. A number of contributors comment on the US-centrism of the first wave of EJ research, but chapters discussing US case studies do not critically reflect on their location. Sze et al.’s chapter title refers simply to ‘the Delta’ (my emphasis). Kurtz’s chapter, despite what sometimes appear to be broader claims, is singularly focused on the American (United States) state. This is of course not to suggest that other states are not racialized, but rather that specific histories and geographies have racialized the Canadian, English, Brazilian and so on states in different ways. On the other hand, Kurtz’s demand for a more careful theorization of the (racial) state and its role in EJ conflicts is important, and remains underdeveloped or unacknowledged in some other chapters. In sum, while the collection does not quite provide a map of the new ‘spaces of environmental justice,’ it does provide signposts that point in a number of useful and provocative directions. Andrew Biro Acadia University, Wolfville, NS, Canada B4P 2R6 andrew.biro@acadiau.ca Review e47© 2015 Macmillan Publishers Ltd. 1470-8914 Contemporary Political Theory Vol. 14, 4, e45–e47 Spaces of environmental justice work_gpqtxuavhvemvouqepfbtwepp4 ---- On Justice Knowledge Activation: Evidence for Spontaneous Activation of Social Justice Inferences Jaap Ham • Kees van den Bos Published online: 1 February 2011 � The Author(s) 2011. This article is published with open access at Springerlink.com Abstract This article focuses on how people infer the justness of events they encounter. Earlier justice research typically asked participants explicitly for their justice judgments. More recent research provided evidence for the possibility of spontaneous judgment inferences. The present research extends this study in three important ways: it provides strong evidence that (1) spontaneous social justice inferences can occur in multiple research paradigms, (2) these inferences constitute a process separate from spontaneous general evaluation of valence, and (3) spon- taneous justice inferences covary with individual differences in sensitivity to justice. We provide evidence for these three conclusions by means of important implicit measurement research paradigms that we specifically tailored to study justice inferences: the probe recognition paradigm and the grid-relearning paradigm. We discuss the implications of our findings for both the literatures on justice and spontaneous inferences. Keywords Social justice � Spontaneous activation � Inferences � Judgments � Probe recognition � Grid relearning Social justice represents a core issue in society, politics, organizations, intimate relationships—indeed in almost every social situation in which people interact with each other (Folger, 1984). Study in various scientific disciplines (ranging from economics to ethology; see, e.g., Beauchamp, 2001) suggests that in their day-to-day J. Ham � K. van den Bos Department of Social and Organizational Psychology, Utrecht University, Utrecht, The Netherlands J. Ham (&) Department of Human-Technology Interaction, Eindhoven University of Technology, IPO 1.36, P.O. Box 513, 5600 MB Eindhoven, The Netherlands e-mail: j.r.c.ham@tue.nl 123 Soc Just Res (2011) 24:43–65 DOI 10.1007/s11211-011-0123-x lives people are exposed to justice-related issues repeatedly. Because all these encounters inherently demand that people assess the justice of what was going on (as justice is not an innate property of a situation but rather in the eye of the beholder; Mikula & Wenzel, 2000), assessing what is just and unjust may be assumed crucial and frequent human activities. Indeed, recent research provides preliminary evidence that individuals spontaneously judge the justness or unjustness of events that they encounter (Ham & Van den Bos, 2008; see also, Correia, Vala, & Aguitar, 2007; Hafer, 2000; Kay & Jost, 2003). That is, there is some tentative evidence suggesting that people can draw social justice inferences without having the intention to form an impression of whether the event that happened was just or unjust (for a more extensive introduction to the concept of spontaneous inferences, see Uleman, 1999; Uleman, Adil Saribay, & Gonzalez, 2008). We think it is important to build and extend on these research studies indicating that people can infer justice levels of situations spontaneously because more systematic evidence for the spontaneous qualities of the justice judgment process is needed. Part of why we think more systematic evidence is needed is conceptual. That is, earlier studies have disputed that individuals consider the justice implications of events spontaneously (see, e.g., Jasso, 1999; Sabbagh, Dar, & Resh, 1994). Related to this, well-known moral psychologists have stated explicitly that assessing morality is caused primarily by careful, intentional reasoning processes (e.g., Kohlberg, 1969; Piaget, 1975; Turiel, 1983) whereas others assume, yet do not show, that assessing morality ‘‘is generally the result of quick, automatic evaluations (intuitions)’’ (Haidt, 2001, p. 814). Another reason why we argue more systematic evidence for spontaneous justice inferences is needed is empirical. For example, most earlier justice studies did not assess the spontaneity of people’s judgments of the justness or unjustness of events and did not use spontaneous justice judgments as their main dependent variables. That is, almost all studies reported in the literature explicitly asked participants or respondents to form justice judgments using explicit measures like Likert-type rating scales to assess justice ratings (for an overview, see, e.g., the appendix in Lind & Tyler, 1988; see also Colquitt & Shaw, 2005). By definition, these kinds of judgments are intentional (Uleman, 1999) and therefore spontaneously formed justice judgments have largely not been assessed (notwithstanding that they may have been activated). There have been earlier articles that, although they did not directly assess the spontaneity of justice judgments, have argued that after many social experiences people may have justice on their minds (see, e.g., Greenberg, 1986, see also, Lerner & Goldberg, 1999). Also, further support for our argument for spontaneous justice judgments can be found in recent studies that suggest that spontaneous activation of justice-related knowledge indeed may occur (Correia et al., 2007; Hafer, 2000; Kay & Jost, 2003). For example, Hafer (2000) found that participants’ implicit reactions to justice-related words were influenced when participants’ beliefs in a just world were threatened. However, these studies (Correia et al., 2007; Hafer, 2000; Kay & Jost, 2003) do not provide direct evidence for spontaneous, unintentional activation of justice-related knowledge: justice judgments may have been intentional in these studies, but they do assess implicit responses related to the activation of the concept of justice. 44 Soc Just Res (2011) 24:43–65 123 More recently there has been direct evidence reporting that people may spontaneously draw inferences about social justice when they encounter events that may or may not strongly threaten their just-world beliefs (Ham & Van den Bos, 2008). That is, in two studies we investigated the social justice inferences people draw after reading descriptions that are highly personally relevant (e.g., ‘‘You and your colleague do the same work. You make 1400 euros a month and your colleague makes 4100 euros a month’’) versus after reading descriptions of lower personal relevance (e.g., ‘‘He and his colleague do the same work. He makes 1400 Euros a month and his colleague makes 4100 Euros a month’’). In both studies, we not only assessed intentional inferences about social justice (using explicit Likert-type justice judgment scales), but also assessed spontaneous justice inferences (using an implicit measurement paradigm: the probe recognition paradigm). Results indicated that participants drew inferences about justice spontaneously. Furthermore, the personal relevance manipulation did not affect intentional inferences about social justice, but did influence spontaneous justice inferences. That is, spontaneous justice inferences were stronger following the reading of descriptions of high personal relevance than descriptions of lower personal relevance. Building on this insight we will present self-relevant descriptions to our participants in the current experiments, noting that spontaneous justice inferences are possible also using descriptions that are less self- relevant. The Current Research Our 2008 findings were the first direct evidence for spontaneous justice inferences using an implicit research paradigm that is well-suited to assess spontaneous inferences (Uleman, Hon, Roman, & Moskowitz, 1996) and provide preliminary evidence for the idea that people spontaneously draw inferences about social justice (Ham & Van den Bos, 2008). The present research extends on the earlier research in three important ways: a first aim of the current research is to provide more robust evidence that spontaneous social justice inferences can occur, using multiple research paradigms. That is, we will provide evidence from the probe recognition paradigm that we used in our earlier research (Ham & Van den Bos, 2008), and from a new research paradigm as well (the grid-relearning paradigm). Obtaining evidence from multiple paradigms is important before reliable conclusions about spontaneous inferences can be drawn (see, e.g., Uleman, 1999). A second aim of the current research is to provide evidence that spontaneous social justice inferences constitute a process separate from spontaneous general evaluation of valence. We think it is necessary to test this prediction, because a critic might argue that the spontaneity of justice inferences simply constitutes a process of merely evaluating the positivity or negativity of events as opposed to more specific spontaneous evaluation of justice inferences. Thus, it is important to show a difference in spontaneous justice inferences as compared to spontaneous valence evaluation (Fazio, 2001). The second aim of this article, therefore, is to test the specificity of the spontaneity of justice inferences versus more general spontaneous valence evaluation. Soc Just Res (2011) 24:43–65 45 123 A third aim is to show that spontaneous justice inferences can covary with individual differences in sensitivity to justice. Research suggests that people differ in the strength with which they react to just and unjust events. These individual differences can be measured by means of the justice sensitivity scale (JSS) developed by Schmitt (1996; Schmitt, Gollwitzer, Maes, & Arbach, 2005). This scale consists of three subscales, of which the first subscale (JSSVictim) measures sensitivity with regard to experiencing injustice towards oneself. The second subscale (JSSPerpetrator) measures sensitivity to profiting oneself from unjust events. The third subscale (JSSObserver) measures sensitivity to observing that others are treated unjustly. We argue here that the more sensitive people are to issues of social justice, the more they will spontaneously draw inferences about social justice. From a functional perspective, it can very well be stated that functionally it would make the most sense if people high in sensitivity to issues of social justice would be able to form adequate justice judgments most spontaneously. Therefore, in line with earlier findings from the social-cognitive literature that higher mental processes that occur often tend to become automatized (Smith, 1994; see also Smith & Lerner, 1986), we propose that people who are strongly sensitive to justice issues may have made justice judgments more frequently, and, thereby, are more likely to draw spontaneous justice inferences than people who are less strongly sensitive to justice issues. Earlier research did not test this prediction, and we think it is important to show evidence for this hypothesis because it will lead to a better view on the mechanisms leading to spontaneous justice inferences. Experiment 1 In social cognition research, the automaticity of higher mental processes has been studied extensively. Findings show, for instance, that after reading the behavior description ‘‘John gets an A for the test,’’ the trait inference ‘‘smart’’ might be spontaneously activated (e.g., Ham & Vonk, 2003). In addition to the reasons mentioned earlier, we think it is interesting to investigate the spontaneity of social justice inferences because we would like to try to integrate the social cognition and social justice literatures; domains of social psychology that have been developed in largely independent ways yet that may profit from each other’s insights. Building on the literature on spontaneous trait inferences, therefore, we used implicit measures to find evidence for spontaneous justice inferences. Specifically, we used two important different implicit measurement paradigms to find evidence for sponta- neous justice inferences: probe recognition and grid-relearning paradigms (Uleman, Newman, & Moskowitz, 1996). In both the experiments of this article, we presented participants with descriptions that implied a just event or an unjust event had happened as well as with descriptions that did not imply anything related to justice. After this, we measured spontaneous justice inferences using these implicit measurement paradigms. In Experiment 1, we assessed participants’ spontaneous justice inferences by means of the probe recognition paradigm (McKoon & Ratcliff, 1986). In this research paradigm, participants read a short description of a situation after which a 46 Soc Just Res (2011) 24:43–65 123 probe word was presented on their screens. Participants were asked to accurately indicate as quickly as possible whether this probe word was part of the sentence they read. For example, participants in our experimental trials read the sentence ‘‘You and your colleague do the same work. You make 1400 Euros a month, and you colleague 4100 Euros,’’ while on control trials they read a sentence that used the same words (including identical pronouns to refer to the actor) but which did not imply anything related to social justice. After such a sentence had been presented, the word ‘‘just’’ was presented on participants’ computer screen and participants were asked to indicate whether this probe word was part of the sentence they had read. If justice inferences are spontaneously drawn while reading the experimental description, then we should find that participants need more time to respond and/or more often respond incorrectly on experimental trials as compared to control trials (the probe recognition effect). This is because the spontaneous justice inference might have interfered with correctly and quickly rejecting the probe word after reading a description that did imply that probe word more so than after reading a description that did not (McKoon & Ratcliff, 1986). Therefore, finding the probe recognition effect indicates that participants spontaneously drew justice inferences. Additionally, in the probe recognition paradigm, participants must suppress drawing spontaneous inferences to respond quickly and correctly as instructed. Therefore, this paradigm provides strong evidence that inferring the probe concepts is not only unintended but also difficult to control (McKoon & Ratcliff, 1986). What makes the probe recognition paradigm especially suited to study spontaneous justice inferences is that, by its very nature, it pits ostensible task demands against spontaneous inferences (Uleman, Hon, et al., 1996). That is, to respond quickly and correctly as instructed, participants must suppress drawing inferences about social justice. Thereby, this paradigm provides strong evidence that a justice inference was formed without intentions to do so, and in efficient, and, especially, uncontrolled ways (see Bargh, 1994). Additionally, characteristics of the probe recognition paradigm are such that awareness of the formation of a justice inference is avoided (McKoon & Ratcliff, 1986; Uleman, Newman, et al., 1996). That is, one of the important characteristics of the probe recognition paradigm is that of all the descriptions presented to participants in this paradigm, justice-related descriptions need only be a small minority. More specifically, our participants are only presented justice-related descriptions on 4 of all 60 descriptions, and awareness of the formation of a justice inference is thereby hidden between interpreting an abundance of other (filler) descriptions. In sum, the probe recognition paradigm can provide strong evidence that spontaneous justice inferences can be formed during reading of situation descriptions that portray a just or an unjust event. More specifically, the probe recognition paradigm uses short description as stimulus material to guarantee implicit measurement and spontaneity of cognitive activity (see McKoon & Ratcliff, 1986). Therefore, we developed and pre-tested four different, short descriptions of justice-implying situations. Of all four descriptions, we developed three versions; a just-implying version and an unjust- implying version (e.g., a description of a just [unjust] event was: ‘‘On the first class, the professor states that 2 [1] of 2 assignments must be handed in. After the course, both assignments are used to calculate your grade’’); and a control version. All three Soc Just Res (2011) 24:43–65 47 123 versions used identical words. The just-implying and the unjust-implying versions solely differed in numbers or amounts mentioned (e.g., ‘‘2’’ or ‘‘1’’) such that they either implied just or unjust events. Some of the four experimental descriptions involved distributive justice, some procedural justice. The control version presented the words (of either the just-implying or the unjust-implying version) in a different order such that these control descriptions formed logical sentences that did not imply anything related to justice (e.g., ‘‘On the first class, the professor states assignment calculations used in both 2 grades. After the course, the 2 [1] assignments must be handed in.’’). All descriptions were self-involving because earlier research (Ham & Van den Bos, 2008) suggests that highly self-relevant justice-related situation descriptions cause stronger spontaneous justice inferences than low self-relevant descriptions. A pretest (Pretest 1, described in Footnote 1) indicated that for all four different descriptions, the three versions indeed were perceived to be just, unjust, and neutral on a dimension of unjust to just. 1 Our predictions were that we would find effects on the probe recognition measures indicating that participants draw justice inferences spontaneously when they read the descriptions that implied just or unjust events. Furthermore, we used our implicit measurement paradigms also to assess spontaneous evaluations of general valence, and, thus, to explore the possible differences between spontaneous justice inferences and spontaneous valence evaluation. Method Participants and Design Participants were 89 students (25 men and 64 women) at Utrecht University. All participants were native Dutch speakers. For a participation of 20 min they received 2 Euros (1 Euro equaled approximately $1.20 U.S. at the time the studies in this paper were conducted). All participants were submitted to a 2 (trial type: experimental vs. control) 9 2 (description: just-implying vs. unjust-implying) 9 2 (probe type: justice-related vs. valence-related) within participants design. 1 In Pretest 1, 160 participants were asked to evaluate how just (1 = very unjust, 7 = very just), fair (1 = very unfair, 7 = very fair), appropriate (1 = very inappropriate, 7 = very appropriate), and justified (1 = very unjustified, 7 = very justified) they thought the events described in the sentences to be. For each sentence, participant’s answers to these four items were averaged to form a reliable scale of their justice judgments (for each sentence, alpha [ .84). Results indicated that events described in just- implying descriptions were indeed judged to be more just (on average, M = 6.3, SD = 1.4) than unjust- implying descriptions (on average, M = 1.5, SD = 0.9), ps \ .001, for all four descriptions. Also, the control version of each sentence was judged (M = 4.3, SD = 1.2) to be more just than the unjust- implying version, ps \ .001, for all four descriptions, and less just than the just-implying descriptions, ps \ .001, for all four descriptions. Furthermore, an analysis of response times to these questions did not show a difference in response times influenced by description type, F \ 1. Therefore, Pretest 1 shows that, as intended, that processing times of the three types of descriptions are comparable. 48 Soc Just Res (2011) 24:43–65 123 Stimulus Materials In our probe recognition paradigm, participants completed 60 trials in random order. In each trial, a short description and a single probe word were presented to the participants. Of the 60 trials, 8 trials (4 experimental and 4 control trials) were the critical trials that were used to test our hypotheses. In the 4 experimental trials, each description was succeeded by a probe word that was implied by the description. Two experimental trials each employed a description implying just events, whereas the remaining 2 experimental trials each employed a description implying unjust events. In both these 2 sets of 2 experimental trials, the probe word was a justice-related word in one trial, and a valence-related word in the other trial. The 4 control trials were similar to the 4 experimental trials, but used descriptions that presented the words (of either the just-implying or the unjust- implying version) in a different order such that these control descriptions formed logical sentences that did not imply anything related to social justice. All descriptions are available on request. So, to keep words used in the control descriptions completely the same as in the experimental descriptions, we used control descriptions in two versions: either the control description used completely the same words as the just-implying experimental description or completely the same words as the unjust-implying experimental description. For the 2 experimental trials employing a justice-related probe word and the corresponding control trials, 2 probe words were taken randomly from a set of 8 words related to social justice. As just probe words we used ‘‘just,’’ ‘‘fair,’’ ‘‘justified,’’ and ‘‘appropriate,’’ and as unjust probe words we used ‘‘unjust,’’ ‘‘unfair,’’ ‘‘unjustified,’’ and ‘‘inappropri- ate.’’ 2 Using both just and unjust probe words allowed us to assess differences in activation levels between these two types of justice-related probes. For the 2 experimental trials employing a valence-related probe word and the corresponding control trials, 2 probe words were taken randomly from a set of 4 words related to general valence evaluation. The positive probe words ‘‘positive’’ and ‘‘friendly’’ represented positive evaluation, and the negative probe words ‘‘negative’’ and ‘‘hateful’’. The valence of all probe words was assessed in Pretest 2. 3 For all trials, at random a description and a concurring probe were chosen with this restriction that no 2 trials used the same materials. 2 All stimulus materials presented are the English translations of the Dutch materials we used. 3 In Pretest 2, implicit general valence evaluations of all cue words used in Experiments 1 and 2 were assessed using a measure of implicit evaluation (the Extrinsic Affective Simon Task or EAST; see De Houwer, 2003). In the EAST, participants see white words that need to be classified on the basis of stimulus valence and colored words that need to be classified on the basis of color. One can estimate participants’ general valence evaluation of a stimulus by presenting that stimulus on the colored trials and comparing the time needed to give the extrinsically positive response (i.e., the response that has to be made to positive white words) with the time needed to give an extrinsically negative response (i.e., the response that has to be made to negative white words). If on the colored trials, the extrinsically positive response is given more quickly and with fewer errors than the extrinsically negative response, one can infer that the stimulus presented on those trials is positive. If the reverse is true, then the stimulus is evaluated negatively. Soc Just Res (2011) 24:43–65 49 123 In addition to the 8 critical trials, 52 filler trials unrelated to social justice were included in the experiment for two reasons. First, if all materials were justice- related, we would not be able to show that it is specifically spontaneity of justice inferences (as opposed to other, more general inferences) that we are revealing here (McKoon & Ratcliff, 1986). Second, if all correct responses were to answer ‘‘no,’’ attending to the description would not be necessary to complete the task (McKoon & Ratcliff, 1986). Therefore, in 30 of the 52 filler trials the probe was a word that was literally in the description. Filler descriptions and probe words were comparable in length and sentence structure to the critical descriptions and probe words. Experimental Procedure The experiment was run on a computer and started with an explanation of the first task. The first task was the probe recognition task which started with a practice round of 12 trials. The practice rounds were the same as the trials of the experimental task, but materials were unrelated to social justice. Next, the 60 trials of the main task started. In each trial, first a row of X’s appeared in the middle of the screen for 1000 ms. Next, the description was displayed for 3000 ms, followed by a blank screen lasting 500 ms. Again a row of X’s appeared on screen for 500 ms, this time followed by the probe. During the whole task the words ‘‘yes’’ and ‘‘no’’ remained visible on the right and left side of the screen. From the moment the probe was presented, participants could press the appropriate keys (the ‘‘a’’-key and the ‘‘6’’-key to indicate ‘‘no’’ and ‘‘yes,’’ respectively) to give their answer. The probe Footnote 3 continued Specifically, the 40 participants of Pretest 2 completed an EAST that used 4 sets of words: 2 sets of valence-related words (2 positive and 2 negative) and the justice-related words (2 just-related and 2 unjust-related) of Experiments 1 and 2. Within participants, we manipulated set contents (justice-related or valence-related words) and set valence (positive or negative). For each set, we calculated an EAST response time score and an EAST error rate score, identical to De Houwer (2003, Study 2). Positive EAST scores indicate that the stimulus presented on those trials is evaluated positive, whereas negative EAST scores indicate negative valence evaluation. We analyzed EAST response time scores and EAST error rate scores (as De Houwer, 2003) for the 4 sets of cue words in two separate 2 (set contents: justice- related vs. valence-related) x 2 (set valence: positive vs. negative) repeated measures ANOVA’s. In both analyses, we found the expected interaction effect; for EAST response time scores, F(1, 39) = 4.85, p \ .05; for EAST error rate scores, F(1, 39) = 5.00, p \ .05. As expected, inspection of means reveals that for valence-related cue words differences in EAST scores between positive and negative sets are bigger than for justice-related cue words. That is, the interaction effect indicated that for EAST response time scores, valence-related positive set scores (M = 40 ms, SD = 55 ms) differed more from valence- related negative set scores (M = -37 ms, SD = 51 ms), F(1, 39) = 45.83, p \ .001, g2 = .54, than justice-related positive set scores (M = 16 ms, SD = 54 ms) differed from justice-related negative set scores (M = -24 ms, SD = 50 ms), F (1, 39) = 10.25, p \ .01, g2 = .21. Similarly, for EAST error rate scores the above mentioned interaction effect showed that the difference between valence-related positive and negative error rate scores (Ms = 1.17% vs. -0.98%, SDs = .95 and .76%) was bigger, F(1, 39) = 104.36, p \ .001, g2 = .73, than the difference between justice-related positive and negative error rate scores (Ms = .81% vs. -0.73%, SDs = 1.03 and .89%), F(1, 39) = 62.39, p \ .001, g2 = .61. These findings show that the cue words representing valence evaluation are evaluated more extreme on a scale of valence than are words representing justice. As intended, this made our valence-related words better suited for assessing automatic general evaluation than our justice-related words (cf. De Houwer, 2003), because, as expected, these results show that they lead to stronger implicit evaluations. 50 Soc Just Res (2011) 24:43–65 123 remained visible until the participant had pressed one of both keys. After the answer was given, a blank screen was displayed for 1000 ms. Then, the next trial started. After completing all trials, participants completed the most recent version of the justice sensitivity scales (Schmitt et al., 2005). For each subscale, participants had to indicate on a 7-point Likert scale how much they agreed with 10 different statements (1 = totally disagree, 7 = totally agree). Participants’ answers to each set of 10 questions were averaged to form three reliable scales of JSSVictim (alpha = .78), JSSObserver (alpha = .89), and JSSPerpetrator (alpha = .86). An example of a JSSVictim statement is ‘‘It bothers me when others receive something that ought to be mine.’’ An example of a JSSObserver statement is ‘‘I am upset when someone does not get a reward he/she has earned.’’ And an example of a JSSPerpetrator statement is ‘‘I cannot easily bear to unilaterally profit from others.’’ Finally, participants were thanked, paid for their participation and debriefed. Results Response Latencies All participants had a low error rate (M = 5.7%, ranging from 0 to 11.2%). Response latencies were analyzed only if the reaction had been a correct one. As recommended by Ratcliff (1993), we analyzed our response latency data by using two methods. First, an absolute cutoff criterion of \200 and [2000 ms was used. Second, an inverse transformation (1/x) of the response latencies was used. The analyses reported hereafter are based on the cutoff criterion, which yielded converging results to the inverse transformation analysis. By using the cutoff point criterion, only a total of 7 responses (0.16%) from 5 participants had to be dropped from the statistical analyses. Response latencies were submitted to a 2 (trial type: experimental vs. control) 9 2 (description: just-implying vs. unjust-implying) 9 2 (probe type: justice-related vs. valence-related) repeated measures analysis of variance (ANOVA). We found corroborative evidence for our research hypotheses. That is, we found evidence for spontaneous justice inferences, indicated by an interaction between trial type and probe type, F(1, 83) = 5.67, p \ .05. As predicted, for justice-related probe words, participants responded slower on experimental trials (M = 699, SD = 174) than on control trials (M = 639, SD = 204), F(1, 83) = 13.15, p \ .01. For valence-related probe words, participants did not respond slower on experimental trials than on control trials (overall M = 651, SD = 215), F \ 1. So, as expected, participants were slower in rejecting justice-related probe words on experimental trials (after reading a description that implied just or unjust events) than on a control trials (after reading a justice-unrelated control description), whereas for valence-related probe words this effect was weaker, in fact was statistically not significant. Furthermore, there was no statistical evidence that descriptions implying just events led to different probe recognition effects than descriptions implying unjust events, as indicated by a non-significant interaction between trial type and description, F \ 1, and between trial type, description, and probe type, F \ 1. Soc Just Res (2011) 24:43–65 51 123 We also examined whether the 4 just probe words led to different probe recognition effects than the 4 unjust probe words. Because we only allowed for a minimum number of 2 experimental trials to contain only materials (description and probe word) related to justice, each participant saw only two of the four possible combinations of the two types of descriptions (just-implying or unjust-implying) and the two types of justice-related probe words (just and unjust probe words). Because of randomization of these combinations, there were two specific subsets of participants that did see the trials relevant for the current analyses. That is, one subset saw only just probe words and a sentence implying a just event on the one and an unjust event on the other of the two experimental trials. Another subset saw only unjust probe words combined with both a sentence implying a just event and one implying an unjust event. So, we could perform two separate 2 (trial type: experimental vs. control) 9 2 (description: just-implying vs. unjust-implying) repeated measures ANOVAs for the two subsets of participants. Results indicate probe recognition effects for both types of probe words: For just probe words, participants responded slower on experimental trials (M = 667, SD = 181) than on control trials (M = 618, SD = 195), F(1, 20) = 4.44, p \ .05, and for unjust probe words, this pattern was also found (M = 689, and SD = 134, versus M = 599, and SD = 168), F(1, 20) = 7.37, p \ .05, independent of whether the sentence implied just or unjust events, all Fs \ 1. Likewise, we performed two separate ANOVAs identical to those used to analyze response times to justice-related probe words, now to explore whether the positive valence-related probe words led to different response times than negative valence- related probe words. Results indicate no overall probe recognition effects for both types of probe words: Neither for positive nor for negative valence-related probe words did we find a main effect of trial type, both Fs \ 1. However, we did find that descriptions that implied a just event led to spontaneous activation of positive valence evaluation. That is, for positive valence-related probe words, we found an interaction between trial type and description: Simple effect analyses revealed that when the description implied a just event, participants responded slower to positive valence-related probe words on experimental trials (M = 739, SD = 263) than on control trials (M = 635, SD = 177), F(1, 20) = 4.73, p \ .05, but not when then the description implied an unjust event, F \ 1. For negative valence-related probe- words, this interaction was not found, F \ 1. Error rates Because no selection criteria apply in this analysis, all error rates of the 89 participants could be analyzed in repeated measures ANOVA identical to the one used to analyze response latencies. 4 This analysis showed results comparable to the analysis of response latencies: The interaction effect between trial type and probe type was significant, F(1, 88) = 17.98, p \ .001. For justice-related probes, participants made more errors on experimental trials (M = 6.49%, SD = 0.58%) 4 When analyzing error rates, we will analyze binomial data—i.e., answers were either correct or wrong. For analyses of variance on binomial data, see Kirk (1982). 52 Soc Just Res (2011) 24:43–65 123 than on control trials (M = 4.04%, SD = 0.57%), F(1, 88) = 33.94, p \ .001. For probes related to evaluation, this difference in error rates was not found (overall M = 5.59%, SD = 0.60%), F \ 1. Furthermore, as in the analyses of participants’ response times, there was no evidence that descriptions implying just events led to different error rates than did descriptions implying unjust events, as suggested by a non-significant interaction between trial type and description, F \ 1, and between trial type, description, and probe type, F \ 1. Finally, comparable to the response time results, further analyses of error rates for just versus unjust probe words indicated probe recognition effects for both just as well as unjust probe words. Two separate repeated measures ANOVA’s, identical to those used to analyze response times of just and unjust probe words, showed that participants made more errors on experimental trials than on control trials, both for just-related probe words, F(1, 22) = 6.52, p \ .05, as well as for unjust-related probe words, F(1, 21) = 8.89, p \ .01, independent of description type, all Fs \ 1. We also performed identical ANOVAs to assess probe recognition effects on error rates for positive and negative valence-related probe words. Comparable to analyses of response times on the two types of valence-related probe words, results did not show that participants made more errors on experimental trials than on control trials for positive nor for valence-related probe words. However, different from analyses on response times to positive valence-related probe words, the analyses of error rates did not suggest that descriptions that implied a just event led to activation of spontaneous positive valence evaluation. That is, for positive evaluation-related probe words, we did not find an interaction between trial type and description in the analysis of error rates, F(1, 22) = 1.53, p = .23, and a simple main effect of trial type was not found for descriptions implying a just event nor descriptions implying an unjust event, Fs \ 1. For negative valence-related probe words, comparable to the analyses of response times, differences in error rates between descriptions types were not found, F \ 1. Insights from Differences in Justice Sensitivity An additional, intriguing aspect of the current findings is that they suggest that spontaneous justice inferences and individual differences in justice sensitivity may be correlated. Specifically, we analyzed whether participants’ scores on the three subscales of the justice sensitivity scale (JSS) were related to the spontaneous activation of the justice-related probe words. To this end, we constructed a measure representing the spontaneous activation of justice-related probe words by subtract- ing participants’ response times on control trials from their response times on experimental trials (collapsing across just-implying and unjust-implying descrip- tions). A regression analysis on this measure for spontaneous justice inferences, showed that of the three subscales of the JSS (JSSVictim, JSSObserver, JSSPerpetrator), JSSVictim, Beta = .236, t(85) = 1.96, p \ .05, and JSSPerpetrator, Beta = .238, t(85) = 2.12, p \ .05, were significantly related to participants’ spontaneous justice inferences. This suggests that especially individual differences in sensitivity to experiences of own injustice and sensitivity towards profiting from unfair events may be strongly associated with spontaneous justice inferences. Soc Just Res (2011) 24:43–65 53 123 Discussion In accordance with our expectations, Experiment 1 presents evidence for spontaneous justice inferences. That is, when participants had read a justice- implying description and the probe word was justice-related, participants were slower and made more errors on rejecting the probe. This suggests that a justice inference was drawn spontaneously while reading our experimental descriptions and that this spontaneous justice inference interfered with quickly and correctly rejecting the probe. Because the probe recognition paradigm was designed to guarantee spontaneity of activation of inferences (see, Uleman, 1999), and hence not giving participants any intentions or instructions to start forming justice judgments), the findings of Experiment 1 indicate that people can activate concerns for social justice in unintended ways when witnessing justice-related events. The findings of Experiment 1 also indicate that spontaneously drawing an inference about social justice is not necessarily the same as more general, spontaneous processes of valence evaluation, as the findings obtained in our probe recognition paradigm clearly indicated stronger activation by our justice-implying descriptions for justice-related probe words than for valence-related probe words. That is, the results indicate only spontaneous justice inferences, but, overall, no spontaneous activation of valence evaluation. Importantly, the results did suggest that the probe recognition paradigm we used in Experiment 1 is sensitive to detecting spontaneous valence evaluation. That is, when our participants had read a description that implied a just event, participants were slower on rejecting positive valence-related probe, although they did not make more errors. This suggests that positive valence has been spontaneously activated while reading those descriptions as it interfered with quickly rejecting the probe. This indicates that some spontaneous valence evaluation has occurred. In Experiment 2, we will use another implicit measurement paradigm to study the robustness of the effects reported in Experiment 1. Finally, we also obtained evidence that individual differences in sensitivity to experiences of own injustice and sensitivity toward profiting from unfair events may be strongly associated with spontaneous justice inferences. We did not find differences in activation of just-related from unjust-related concepts dependent on whether a description implied a just or an unjust event. We will come back to these findings after we have reported the findings of our second experiment. Experiment 2 One important aim of Experiment 2 was to replicate the findings obtained in Experiment 1 using a different research paradigm. To this end, we adapted another implicit measurement paradigm to detect spontaneous justice inferences: the ‘‘grid- relearning paradigm.’’ This paradigm was recently developed by Ham and Vonk (2003) to study the activation of spontaneous inferences in person perception. It is in general based on the notion that relearning is more effective than learning, and more specifically on research by Carlston and Skowronski (1994), and on the idea that 54 Soc Just Res (2011) 24:43–65 123 implicit inferences are learned when they initially occur, so that when the same material is encountered later on in explicit learning trials, it is essentially relearned and hence learned more quickly. In the grid-relearning paradigm, we developed for the line of research presented here, participants had the opportunity to learn a combination two times. That is, in the three tasks of this paradigm, participants are presented with a 4 9 4 information-grid. In the first task, in each cell of the grid, a description is presented. For example, one unjust-implying description that we used was: ‘‘You and your colleague do the same work. You make 1400 euros a month and your colleague makes 4100 euros a month.’’ This description was presented to the participants in a certain cell of the 4 9 4 grid and the only instruction participants received was to read this sentence. In the second task, cue words are presented in each cell and participants are asked to remember which word was presented in which cell. Finally, in the third task, recall for which word was presented in which cell is tested. In some cases (labeled a relearning trial), the cue word presented in the second task is an implication of the description presented in that same cell in the previous task. For example, ‘‘unjust’’ is presented in the same cell as where the unjust- implying description was presented. In such a case, assuming that a justice inference is already drawn spontaneously while reading the description during the first task (since no instructions were given to participants to form justice judgments), 5 this implies that participants are now learning a combination they already saw before. In effect, then, they are relearning the combination. In other cases (labeled control trials), the cue word presented in the second task is not an implication of the description presented in that same cell in the first task. For example, ‘‘unjust’’ is presented in the same cell as where a description that did not imply something related to justice was presented in the first task. So, in the control trials, relearning does not occur because a spontaneous justice inference cannot have been drawn while reading this description. If a justice inference is drawn spontaneously while reading the justice-implying description in the first task, recall should be better in relearning trials than in control trials, because in case of the relearning trial, the first exposure should have produced a residual effect that facilitates learning in the second task. These facilitation effects (Carlston & Skowronski, 1994; Ham & Vonk, 2003), were used here to study the possibility of spontaneous justice inferences in Experiment 2. 5 Indeed, not giving instructions to form a justice inference does not necessarily mean that people did not intentionally form one. However, as the relearning paradigm does give participants another instruction (namely to read the sentences presented to them), this research paradigm (see also Carlston & Skowronski, 1994) argues that they were not given the intention to form justice inferences but rather other intentions, and therefore, that participants (if the relearning effect is found) drew justice inferences spontaneously, that is, without haven been given the intention. People may spontaneously come up with the intention to draw justice inferences (instead of doing what we ask them: read the sentences), but in that case, their intentions would be at least spontaneously formed. Experiment 1 indicates that even when participants need to suppress drawing spontaneous inferences (to respond quickly and correctly as instructed) they still do so. Thereby, the research paradigm used in Experiment 1 indicates that even when something like ‘spontaneous intentions to draw justice inferences’ is inhibited, we find evidence of spontaneous justice inferences. Soc Just Res (2011) 24:43–65 55 123 The relearning paradigm is especially suited for our current means because it has not only been used to assess spontaneous social inferences, but also to assess spontaneous valence evaluation. That is, in a study by Ho, Skowronski, and Carlston (D. Carlston, personal communication, November 11, 2005), the relearning paradigm showed facilitation effects for general valence evaluation terms like ‘‘positive’’ and ‘‘negative,’’ indicating that valence evaluation spontaneously occurred when participants were presented with positive or negative valence- implying (behavior) descriptions, and can be detected by relearning paradigms. Because the experimental descriptions we used in Experiment 2 were specifically tailored to reflect justice-related issues, we expected participants who have been presented just-implying and unjust-implying descriptions to show stronger facili- tation effects for cue words that are related to justice than for cue words related to general valence evaluation, and exploratively we examined whether facilitation effects on general valence evaluation would be found in our justice-related relearning paradigm. Method Participants and Design Ninety-four students (33 men and 61 women) at Utrecht University participated in this experiment. All participants were native Dutch speakers and received 2 Euros for their participation of approximately 20 min. Participants were submitted to a 3 (trial type: relearning just-implying description vs. relearning unjust-implying description vs. control) 9 2 (cue type: justice-related word vs. valence-related word) within participants design. Stimulus Materials In the experiment, each participant completed 16 trials. Ten of these trials were filler trials and 6 were experimental trials. In each trial, a short description and a single cue word were presented to the participants. In the 6 experimental trials, each participant was presented with 2 just-implying descriptions, 2 unjust-implying descriptions, and 2 justice-unrelated descriptions. The descriptions were presented in a randomized order to participants. The just-implying and unjust-implying descriptions used in Experiment 2 are identical to those used in Experiment 1. The justice-unrelated descriptions were 2 general personality-trait-implying descriptions, taken at random from a set of 12 descriptions used in earlier research using this paradigm (see Ham & Vonk, 2003, Appendix, Descriptions 1–12). Finally, on the 10 filler trials, the remaining 10 descriptions from the Ham and Vonk (2003) materials were used. The cue words used on the experimental trials of Experiment 2 were identical to the justice-related and valence-related probe words used in Experiment 1. Like the descriptions, cue words used on the 10 filler trials were identical to those used in earlier research using this paradigm (see Ham & Vonk, 2003, Appendix, Trait words 1–10). For each experimental trial, at random a description and a cue word were chosen with this restriction that no two trials used the same materials. 56 Soc Just Res (2011) 24:43–65 123 Overview of the Grid-Relearning Paradigm The grid-relearning paradigm consisted of three main tasks: an exposure task, a relearning task, and a cued-recall task. In each task, a grid of 4 9 4 cells was displayed on participants’ screens. In the exposure task, 16 descriptions were presented: One by one, in random order and randomly distributed among the cells of the grid, a description was displayed for 6 s. In the relearning task, a randomly ordered cue word was displayed for 4 s in one of the cells. Participants were instructed to memorize which word was displayed in which cell. In half of the trials—the relearning trials—the cue word fitted an implication of the description that had been presented in the same cell during the exposure task. In the other half of the trials—the control trials—the displayed cue word did not fit an implication of the description presented in the same cell. Thus, these control trials did not allow relearning. Finally, during the cued-recall task, participants were asked to recall what cue word was shown in which cell in the relearning task. So, the grid-relearning paradigm consists of 16 trials, of which 8 were relearning trials and 8 were control trials. Of all 16 trials, 3 trials (2 of the 8 relearning trials and 1 of the 8 control trials) were used to detect spontaneous justice inferences and the other 3 trials (2 of the remaining 6 relearning trials and 1 of the remaining 7 control trials) were used to detect spontaneous evaluation of valence. The design of the current study only applies to these 6 trials. The remaining 10 trials (4 relearning trials and 6 control trials) were filler trials that did not use material related to justice. As in Experiment 1, the filler trials were included mainly to keep the ratio of justice- related descriptions to justice-unrelated descriptions low. Cue type was manipulated within the six experimental trials: In 3 trials, the cue word used in the relearning task was a justice-related word, and in the other 3 trials a valence-related word. Also within these 6 experimental trials, thus within subjects, trial type was manipulated. That is, participants completed two relearning trials that used a just-implying description, two relearning trials that used an unjust-implying description and two control trials. In the two types of relearning trials, the description was just-implying in the one type of relearning trials, and the description was unjust-implying in the other. In control trials, the descriptions in the exposure task did not imply anything related to just or unjust experiences. Procedure Seated behind a computer screen, participants individually went through the instructions and the tasks. They were told that they would participate in a study investigating communication. After receiving general instructions, participants completed a practice trial, consisting of completing a practice exposure task and a practice cued-recall task (both tasks were unrelated to social justice). After this, the actual experiment began, starting with the exposure task. Participants were asked to read all descriptions to be presented in the 4 9 4 grid. In each cell of the grid, in random order, a description was presented for 6 s. After a description had been presented, the screen turned blank for 2 s and then the next description was displayed in another cell. Soc Just Res (2011) 24:43–65 57 123 Between the exposure and the relearning task, a filler task (consisting of five word puzzles) was inserted to make it less easy for participants to recall the specific information presented in each cell (cf. Carlston & Skowronski, 1994). After the filler task, participants completed the relearning task. Identical to the practice task, participants were asked to remember what cue word was presented in which cell in this task. Each cue word was presented for 2 s in a cell of the grid, and then the screen turned blank for 2 s and the next word was presented in another cell. Between the relearning and the cued-recall task, a second filler task (consisting of a different set of five word puzzles) was inserted. The last task was the cued-recall task. In this task, participants were presented with the words presented in the relearning task, and asked in which cell that cue word had been shown during the relearning task. This question was asked about all 16 words, in random order. Every time, the question was presented underneath the 4 9 4 grid, and participants could answer by clicking on a cell with their mouse. So, the dependent variable indicated whether the participant answered a question correct or false (coded as ‘‘1’’ for a correct answer and ‘‘2’’ for an incorrect answer on a specific trial). After the grid-relearning paradigm, participants completed the justice sensitivity scales, identical to Experiment 1. As in Experiment 1, participants’ answers to each set of 10 questions were averaged to form the three reliable scales of JSSVictim (alpha = .81), JSSObserver (alpha = .86), and JSSPerpetrator (alpha = .82). Finally, participants were debriefed and thanked for their participation. Results and Discussion Facilitation Effects To determine whether we found evidence for spontaneous justice inferences in Experiment 2, we analyzed whether the justice relearning paradigm we developed yielded the facilitation effects predicted by our focal hypothesis of Experiment 2. Therefore, whether participants’ responses to the cued-recall on a trial were correct or incorrect was submitted to a 3 (trial type: relearning just-implying description vs. relearning unjust-implying description vs. control) 9 2 (cue type: justice-related word vs. valence-related word) repeated measures ANOVA (see Footnote 3). A difference in activation of spontaneous justice inferences as compared to sponta- neous valence evaluation would be indicated by facilitation effects on justice-related cue words for relearning trials over control trials. In other words, we expected an interaction between trial type and cue type such that superior recall would be found on the relearning trials for justice-related cue words. This interaction effect between trial type and cue type was indeed found, F(1, 93) = 3.15, p \ .05. As hypothesized, for justice-related cue words, relearning trials led to better recall of cue words than the control trials, indicated by a simple effect of trial type, F(1, 93) = 4.26, p \ .05. That is, a facilitation effect was found for justice-related cue words: Of all participants, 47.3% remembered the relearning trials correctly, whereas 30.9% remembered the control trial correctly, indicated by a contrast comparing (the two types of) relearning trials to control trials, F(1, 93) = 10,03, p \ .001. 58 Soc Just Res (2011) 24:43–65 123 Results of Experiment 2 also mirror those of Experiment 1 by showing that whether the descriptions implied just or unjust events did not influence facilitation effects on recall of justice-related cue words: Contrast analyses showed that the facilitation effect was found both for relearning trials using a just-implying description (in which case 48.9% of the participants answered correctly) compared to control trials (30.9% of the participants answered correctly), F(1, 93) = 7.96, p \ .01, as for relearning trials using an unjust-implying description (45.7% of the participants answered correctly) compared to control trials, F(1, 93) = 5.72, p \ .05. A direct comparison of these two effects suggests that just-implying versus unjust-implying sentences did not lead to better relearning of justice-related cue words, as indicated by a non-significant contrast effect, F \ 1. For valence-related cue words, a facilitation effect following the just- or unjust- implying descriptions was not found: Relearning trials were not remembered better than control trials for these cue words, F \ 1 (overall, 44.3% of the participants answered correctly on these trials). 6 Also, both the contrast of relearning trials using a just-implying description versus control trials and the contrast of relearning trials using an unjust-implying description to control trials were not significant, and also a contrast comparing (the two types of) relearning trials to control trials was not significant, all Fs \ 1. Furthermore, we explored whether the 4 just cue words led to different facilitation effects than the 4 unjust cue words. Replicating the pattern found in Experiment 1, results of Experiment 2 indicate a facilitation effect for both types of cue words: For just cue words, 57.9% of the participants remembered relearning trials correctly, whereas only 34.2% remembered the control trial correctly, F(1, 37) = 6.13, p \ .05, and for unjust cue words, this pattern was also found (58.1–24.3% of the participants), F(1, 37) = 11.24, p \ .01, independent of whether the description implied just or unjust events, Fs \ 1. We also explored whether the 2 positive valence-related cue words led to different facilitation effects than the 2 negative valence-related cue words. Although these analyses in Experiment 1 did reveal some evidence of specific spontaneous valence-evaluations, results of the current experiment did not indicate facilitation effects, neither when the probe word was related to positive or negative valence nor when the description implied a just or an unjust event, Fs \ 1. Insights from Differences in Justice Sensitivity Additionally, Experiment 2 corroborates the findings obtained in Experiment 1 in that spontaneous justice inferences and the same individual differences in justice sensitivity (JSSVictim, JSSPerpetrator) were again significantly related: As in Exper- iment 1, we analyzed whether participants’ scores on the justice sensitivity scale (JSS) subscales were related to a measure we constructed that indicated the strength of spontaneous activation of justice-related cue words. This indication of the 6 A direct comparison between findings for justice-related cue words and valence-related cue words cannot be made because these types of cue words consist of different words that can be more easy or more difficult to remember. Soc Just Res (2011) 24:43–65 59 123 strength of spontaneous justice inferences was calculated by subtracting scores on control trials from scores on experimental trials for trials using justice-related cue words. A regression analysis with all three subscales of the JSS as predictors, and this measure for spontaneous justice inferences as the criterion, again showed JSSPerpetrator, Beta = .34, t(90) = 2.61, p \ .05, and JSSVictim, Beta = .25, t(90) = 2.27, p \ .05, to be significant predictors, whereas JSSObserver was not a significant predictor, Beta = .032, t(90) = .25, p = .80. General Discussion The current findings support and extend earlier research that provided the first evidence for spontaneous justice inferences (Ham & Van den Bos, 2008). That is, the current research provides further evidence that people can draw inferences about the justness of situations spontaneously, using the identical research paradigm to assess spontaneous justice inferences as earlier research (Ham & Van den Bos, 2008; the probe recognition paradigm) but also using a new research paradigm (the grid-relearning paradigm). More specifically, in two experiments, using the two different implicit measurement paradigms, we found evidence that people spontaneously draw inferences about the justness of events. In Experiments 1 and 2, we found evidence that people draw spontaneous inferences about social justice when reading a self-relevant situation description of a just or an unjust event. That is, we found that when people read short situation descriptions that portray just or unjust events, they spontaneously activate social justice inferences, resulting in stronger interference effects in a probe-recognition study (Experiment 1) and stronger facilitation effects in a relearning study (Experiment 2). Because of the features of the currently used research paradigms described earlier (for further details, see Carlston & Skowronski 1994; McKoon & Ratcliff, 1986; see also De Houwer & Moors, 2007), we know that spontaneous justice inferences studied here have been formed in unintentional (indicated by both research paradigms) and uncontrollable (indicated by the probe recognition paradigm, see also, Bargh, 1994) ways by our participants, and we can assume that the justice inferences drawn were activated spontaneously while reading the descriptions (see Uleman, 1999).The current results provide further evidence that in many justice-relevant situations people will draw inferences about justice levels of that situation without the necessity of any intentions to assess justice levels, and without being able to refrain from doing so. Therefore, this finding presents empirical evidence to the ongoing debate on the nature of justice and moral judgments mentioned in the introduction (see, e.g., Haidt, 2001): justice judgments do not necessarily need careful and intentional reasoning, but can also be made unintentionally. An implication of the current findings therefore is that it can be expected that people will spontaneously draw inferences about social justice in justice-relevant situations, also when they are busy doing other things (e.g., Van den Bos, Peters, Bobocel, & Ybema, 2006). Furthermore, the results presented here suggest that spontaneous justice inferences should not be equated with spontaneous general evaluation of valence. That is, both experiments clearly indicated stronger spontaneous justice inferences 60 Soc Just Res (2011) 24:43–65 123 than spontaneous general valence evaluation, indicated by stronger interference effects for justice-related words than for valence-related words in Experiment 1, and stronger facilitation effects for justice-related words than for valence-related words in Experiment 2. Thus, both the experiments show that justice-implying descriptions influenced activation of justice-related words stronger than activation of valence- related words. Had spontaneous justice inferences been a process of more general valence evaluation, we should have found no significant differences between justice-related and valence-related probes or cues, or would have found the opposite pattern of results, because, as Pretest 2 indicates, our valence-related words are evaluated more extreme on a valence dimension than the justice-related words and both research paradigms are sensitive to detecting both spontaneous justice inferences as well as spontaneous valence evaluation. 7 This last aspect of our findings suggests that, on the one hand, as Van den Bos et al. (2008) suggest, the cognitive process of assessing social justice seems to be a process identical in its characteristics to other higher mental processes, but, on the other hand, it also seems to constitute an independent higher mental processes that can have unique qualities, at least in the two experiments presented here. Another major aim of the current manuscript was to assess the relation between our measures of spontaneous justice judgments and sensitivity to issues of social justice. In Experiments 1 and 2, we found that sensitivity for social justice issues (Schmitt, 1996) predicted the strength of spontaneous justice inferences. More precisely, the subscales of JSSVictim and JSSPerpetrator predicted the strength of spontaneous justice inferences, whereas the subscale of JSSObserver did not. This indicates that the more sensitive people are to experiencing injustice towards oneself (JSSVictim) and to profiting themselves from unfair events (JSSPerpetrator), the more strongly they spontaneously drew justice inferences in our studies. Contrastingly, spontaneous justice inferences remained independent of sensitivity to observing that others are treated unfairly (JSSObserver). An explanation for this might be that our stimulus material only used descriptions of justice-relevant situations applied to participants themselves (as, e.g., ‘‘You made a test of 40 questions. Your grade is based on 1 of your 40 answers’’) and did not use descriptions of justice-relevant situations applied to other people. So, interestingly, this suggests that spontaneous justice inferences about self-involving justice-related situations can be predicted by specific sensitivity to issues of social justice, namely sensitivity to self-involving issues (JSSVictim and JSSPerpetrator), and not by sensitivity to other-involving issues of social justice. Future research may want investigate whether spontaneous justice inferences about other-involving justice-related situations can be predicted by sensitivity to other-involving issues of social justice (the JSSObserver subscale). The current findings corroborate our argument for the idea that frequently assessing (self-involving) social justice (reflected in high levels of justice sensitivity) will lead to more spontaneous (self-involving) justice inferences. Thereby, these findings are 7 That is, Experiments 1 and 2 indicate that both research paradigms are sensitive to detection of spontaneous justice inferences. In addition, as mentioned earlier, findings of Experiment 1 suggest that the probe recognition paradigm is sensitive to detecting spontaneous valence evaluation, and earlier research (by Ho, Skowronski, & Carlston; D. Carlston, personal communication, November 11, 2005) successfully used the relearning paradigm of Experiment 2 to detect spontaneous valence evaluation. Soc Just Res (2011) 24:43–65 61 123 relevant to recent work by Baumert and Schmitt (2009) that frames justice sensitivity in terms of the accessibility of justice categories. So, in Experiments 1 and 2 we found evidence for spontaneous inferences about social justice, but no evidence that unjust-implying descriptions lead to stronger automatic activation of justice concerns than just-implying descriptions. Furthermore, the current two studies did also not suggest differences in activation of just-related (e.g., ‘‘just’’) from unjust-related concepts (e.g., ‘‘unjust’’) dependent on whether a description implied a just or an unjust event. This latter finding is in line with the finding that negations of evaluative stimuli (e.g., ‘‘no snakes’’) do not influence spontaneous evaluative responses to these stimuli (Deutsch, Gawronski, & Strack, 2006; but see also Mayo, Schul & Burnstein, 2004), even though spontaneous responses to stimuli that consist of traits versus their antonyms (e.g., ‘‘cruel’’ vs. ‘‘kind’’) can vary (Todorov & Uleman, 2002). A measure of concept activation (as the two research paradigms we used in Experiments 1 and 2) might be very sensitive to activation levels of concepts (represented by words or related words), but might not be the best paradigm to assess activation differences between concepts represented by words related to one another. Future research may employ implicit measurement paradigms that are better suited for these specific questions, and in addition study possible mediators of the strength of spontaneous justice inferences. Recently, Uleman et al. (2008) indicated that spontaneous inferences have been insufficiently linked to other phenomena and theories. The current research makes this link in three ways: By integrating the social cognition (including spontaneous inference literature) and social justice literatures, disentangling spontaneous inferences from spontaneous general evaluations, and assessing the covariance between spontaneous justice inferences and sensitivity to justice. Thereby, it adds important knowledge to the literature on spontaneous inferences. A final merit of the current research we want to mention is that it provides methodological tools that can be used in future research to get more fine-grained insights into the social justice judgment process. That is, we have tailored two precise research paradigms and ditto stimulus materials especially to assess and test spontaneous justice inferences. More broadly, the current findings have important implications for proponents of models in moral psychology and social justice research that assume either controlled or spontaneous cognitive processes for making justice judgments or moral judgments. Because we now have strong and additional evidence that justice judgments can occur spontaneously, we can conclude that not necessarily are controlled processes needed for people to come to justice judgments. Therefore, the current results suggest a disconfirmation of an important assumption of earlier justice models stating that the justice judgment process constitutes a particularly controlled process (see, e.g., Jasso, 1999; Sabbagh et al., 1994). Rather, we can conclude that cognitive reactions to justice-related events probably consist of both spontaneous (as indicated by the current research) and controlled (as indicated by earlier research) processes (see, e.g., Strack & Deutsch, 2004), and future research could investigate the relation between these processes. This could lead to the conclusion that, whether 62 Soc Just Res (2011) 24:43–65 123 born-in (De Waal, 2001) or through socialization (see, e.g., Lerner, Miller, & Holmes, 1976), humans seem to be able to make justice judgments spontaneously. In sum, the current research teaches us several things about justice inferences: it provides strong evidence that spontaneous social justice inferences can occur in multiple research paradigms, these inferences constitute a process separate from spontaneous general evaluation of valence, and spontaneous justice inferences covary with individual differences in sensitivity to justice. Also, we now have available research mechanisms to directly assess these spontaneous justice inferences. Thereby, the current research sheds light on the nature of justice inferences. It suggests that the nature of people’s responses to justice-relevant situations and events might at least partly be spontaneous and unintentional. So, when assessing people’s justice-relevant responses, future research should take into account people’s spontaneous justice inferences. Because reflective cognitions (e.g., controlled justice judgments) and implicit cognitions (e.g., spontaneous justice inferences) relate to behavior differently (Strack & Deutsch, 2004), spontaneous justice inferences might prove to be important determinants of behavior in crucial situations. For example, recent research indicates that implicit attitudes about consumer products are good product choice predictors in situations of high time- constraint (Friese, Waenke, & Plessner, 2006). Future research might investigate the relationship between controlled and spontaneous justice inferences and various kinds of justice-related behavior. Thereby, we would not only uncover more about the nature of justice inferences, but also about the implications of the (spontaneous, implicit) nature of justice inferences on human behavior in society, politics, organizations, and intimate relationships. Acknowledgments The research reported in this article was supported by a VICI innovational research grant from the Netherlands Organization for Scientific Research (NWO, 453.03.603) awarded to Kees van den Bos. We thank Annemarie Loseman for providing the Dutch translation of the justice sensitivity scale. Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution Non- commercial License which permits any noncommercial use, distribution, and reproduction in any med- ium, provided the original author(s) and source are credited. References Bargh, J. A. (1994). The four horsemen of automaticity: Awareness, efficiency, intention, and control in social cognition. In R. S. Wyer Jr. & T. K. Srull (Eds.), Handbook of social cognition (2nd ed., pp. 1–40). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Baumert, A., & Schmitt, M. (2009). Justice-sensitive interpretations of ambiguous situations. Australian Journal of Psychology, 61, 6–12. Beauchamp, T. L. (2001). Philosophical ethics: An introduction to moral philosophy (3rd ed.). Boston: McGraw-Hill. Carlston, D. E., & Skowronski, J. J. (1994). Savings in the relearning of trait information as evidence for spontaneous inference generation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 66, 840–856. Soc Just Res (2011) 24:43–65 63 123 Colquitt, J. A., & Shaw, J. C. (2005). How should organizational justice be measured? In J. Greenberg & J. A. Colquitt (Eds.), Handbook of organizational justice (pp. 113–152). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Correia, I., Vala, J., & Aguitar, P. (2007). Victim’s innocence, social categorization, and the threat to the belief in a just world. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 43, 31–38. De Houwer, J. (2003). The extrinsic affective Simon task. Experimental Psychology, 50, 77–85. De Houwer, J., & Moors, A. (2007). How to define and examine the implicitness of implicit measures. In B. Wittenbrink & N. Schwarz (Eds.), Implicit measures of attitudes (pp. 179–194). New York: Guilford Press. De Waal, F. (2001). The ape and the sushi master: Cultural reflections of a primatologist. New York: Basic Books. Deutsch, R., Gawronski, B., & Strack, F. (2006). At the boundaries of automaticity: Negation as reflective operation. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 91, 386–405. Fazio, R. H. (2001). On the automatic activation of associated evaluations: An overview. Cognition and Emotion, 15, 115–141. Folger, R. (Ed.). (1984). The sense of injustice: Social psychological perspectives. New York: Plenum. Friese, M., Waenke, M., & Plessner, H. (2006). Implicit consumer preferences and their influence on product choice. Psychology & Marketing, 23, 727–740. Greenberg, J. (1986). Determinants of perceived fairness of performance evaluations. Journal of Applied Psychology, 71, 340–342. Hafer, C. L. (2000). Do innocent victims threaten the belief in a just world? Evidence from a modified Stroop task. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 79, 165–173. Haidt, J. (2001). The emotional dog and its rational tail: A social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review, 108, 814–834. Ham, J., & Van den Bos, K. (2008). Not fair for me! The influence of personal relevance on social justice inferences. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 44, 699–705. Ham, J., & Vonk, R. (2003). Smart and easy: Co-occurring activation of spontaneous trait inferences and spontaneous situational inferences. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 39, 434–447. Jasso, G. (1999). How much injustice is there in the world? Two new justice indexes. American Sociological Review, 64, 133–168. Kay, A. C., & Jost, J. T. (2003). Complementary justice: Effects of ‘‘poor but happy’’ and ‘‘poor but honest’’ stereotype exemplars on system justification and implicit activation of the justice motive. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 85, 823–837. Kirk, R. E. (1982). Experimental design: Procedures for the behavioral sciences. Belmont, CA: Brooks/ Cole. Kohlberg, L. (1969). Stage and sequence: The cognitive-developmental approach to socialization. In D. A. Goslin (Ed.), Handbook of socialization theory and research (pp. 347–480). Chicago: Rand McNally. Lerner, M. J., & Goldberg, J. H. (1999). When do decent people blame victims? The differing effects of the explicit/rational and implicit/experiential cognitive systems. In S. Chaiken & Y. Trope (Eds.), Dual-process theories in social psychology (pp. 627–640). New York: Guilford Press. Lerner, M. J., Miller, D. T., & Holmes, J. G. (1976). Deserving and the emergence of forms of justice. In L. Berkowitz & E. Walster (Eds.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 9, pp. 133–162). New York: Academic Press. Lind, E. A., & Tyler, T. R. (1988). The social psychology of procedural justice. New York: Plenum. Mayo, R., Schul, Y., & Burnstein, E. (2004). ‘‘I am not guilty’’ vs ‘‘I am innocent’’: Successful negation may depend on the schema used for its encoding. Journal of Experiment Social Psychology, 40, 433–449. McKoon, G., & Ratcliff, R. (1986). Inferences about predictable events. Journal of Experimental Psychology. Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 12, 82–91. Mikula, G., & Wenzel, M. (2000). Justice and social conflict. International Journal of Psychology, 35, 126–135. Piaget, J. (1975). The moral judgment of the child. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. (Original work published 1932). Ratcliff, R. (1993). Methods for dealing with reaction time outliers. Psychological Bulletin, 114, 510–532. Sabbagh, C., Dar, Y., & Resh, N. (1994). The structure of social justice judgments: A facet approach. Social Psychology Quarterly, 57, 244–261. 64 Soc Just Res (2011) 24:43–65 123 Schmitt, M. (1996). Individual differences in sensitivity to befallen injustice. Personality and Individual Differences, 21, 3–20. Schmitt, M., Gollwitzer, M., Maes, J., & Arbach, D. (2005). Justice sensitivity: Assessment and location in the personality space. European Journal of Psychological Assessment, 21, 202–211. Smith, E. R. (1994). Procedural knowledge and processing strategies in social cognition. In R. S. Wyer Jr. & T. K. Srull (Eds.), Handbook of social cognition: Vol. 1, Basic processes (2nd ed., pp. 99–151). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Smith, E. R., & Lerner, M. (1986). Development of automatism of social judgments. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 50, 246–259. Strack, F., & Deutsch, R. (2004). Reflective and impulsive determinants of social behavior. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 8, 247–320. Todorov, A., & Uleman, J. S. (2002). Spontaneous trait inferences are bound to actors: Evidence from false recognition. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 83, 1051–1065. Turiel, E. (1983). The development of social knowledge: Morality and convention. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Uleman, J. S. (1999). Spontaneous versus intentional inferences in impression formation. In S. Chaiken & Y. Trope (Eds.), Dual-process theories in social psychology (pp. 141–160). New York: Guilford press. Uleman, J. S., Adil Saribay, S., & Gonzalez, C. M. (2008). Spontaneous inferences, implicit impressions and implicit theories. Annual Review of Psychology, 59, 329–360. Uleman, J. S., Hon, A., Roman, R., & Moskowitz, G. B. (1996a). On-line evidence for spontaneous trait inferences at encoding. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 22, 377–394. Uleman, J. S., Newman, L. S., & Moskowitz, G. B. (1996b). People as flexible interpreters: Evidence and issues from spontaneous trait inference. In M. P. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 28, pp. 211–279). San Diego, CA: Academic Press. Van den Bos, K., Ham, J., Lind, E. A., Simonis, M., Van Essen, W. J., & Rijpkema, M. (2008). Justice and the human alarm system: The impact of exclamation points and flashing lights on the justice judgment process. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 44, 201–219. Van den Bos, K., Peters, S. L., Bobocel, D. R., & Ybema, J. F. (2006). On preferences and doing the right thing: Satisfaction with advantageous inequity when cognitive processing is limited. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 42, 273–289. Soc Just Res (2011) 24:43–65 65 123 On Justice Knowledge Activation: Evidence for Spontaneous Activation of Social Justice Inferences Abstract The Current Research Experiment 1 Method Participants and Design Stimulus Materials Experimental Procedure Results Response Latencies Error rates Insights from Differences in Justice Sensitivity Discussion Experiment 2 Method Participants and Design Stimulus Materials Overview of the Grid-Relearning Paradigm Procedure Results and Discussion Facilitation Effects Insights from Differences in Justice Sensitivity General Discussion Acknowledgments References << /ASCII85EncodePages false /AllowTransparency false /AutoPositionEPSFiles true /AutoRotatePages /None /Binding /Left /CalGrayProfile (Gray Gamma 2.2) /CalRGBProfile (sRGB IEC61966-2.1) /CalCMYKProfile (ISO Coated v2 300% \050ECI\051) /sRGBProfile (sRGB IEC61966-2.1) /CannotEmbedFontPolicy /Error /CompatibilityLevel 1.3 /CompressObjects /Off /CompressPages true /ConvertImagesToIndexed true /PassThroughJPEGImages true /CreateJobTicket false /DefaultRenderingIntent /Perceptual /DetectBlends true /DetectCurves 0.1000 /ColorConversionStrategy /sRGB /DoThumbnails true /EmbedAllFonts true /EmbedOpenType false /ParseICCProfilesInComments true /EmbedJobOptions true /DSCReportingLevel 0 /EmitDSCWarnings false /EndPage -1 /ImageMemory 1048576 /LockDistillerParams true /MaxSubsetPct 100 /Optimize true /OPM 1 /ParseDSCComments true /ParseDSCCommentsForDocInfo true /PreserveCopyPage true /PreserveDICMYKValues true /PreserveEPSInfo true /PreserveFlatness true /PreserveHalftoneInfo false /PreserveOPIComments false /PreserveOverprintSettings true /StartPage 1 /SubsetFonts false /TransferFunctionInfo /Apply /UCRandBGInfo /Preserve /UsePrologue false /ColorSettingsFile () /AlwaysEmbed [ true ] /NeverEmbed [ true ] /AntiAliasColorImages false /CropColorImages true /ColorImageMinResolution 149 /ColorImageMinResolutionPolicy /Warning /DownsampleColorImages true /ColorImageDownsampleType /Bicubic /ColorImageResolution 150 /ColorImageDepth -1 /ColorImageMinDownsampleDepth 1 /ColorImageDownsampleThreshold 1.50000 /EncodeColorImages true /ColorImageFilter /DCTEncode /AutoFilterColorImages true /ColorImageAutoFilterStrategy /JPEG /ColorACSImageDict << /QFactor 0.40 /HSamples [1 1 1 1] /VSamples [1 1 1 1] >> /ColorImageDict << /QFactor 0.15 /HSamples [1 1 1 1] /VSamples [1 1 1 1] >> /JPEG2000ColorACSImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 30 >> /JPEG2000ColorImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 30 >> /AntiAliasGrayImages false /CropGrayImages true /GrayImageMinResolution 149 /GrayImageMinResolutionPolicy /Warning /DownsampleGrayImages true /GrayImageDownsampleType /Bicubic /GrayImageResolution 150 /GrayImageDepth -1 /GrayImageMinDownsampleDepth 2 /GrayImageDownsampleThreshold 1.50000 /EncodeGrayImages true /GrayImageFilter /DCTEncode /AutoFilterGrayImages true /GrayImageAutoFilterStrategy /JPEG /GrayACSImageDict << /QFactor 0.40 /HSamples [1 1 1 1] /VSamples [1 1 1 1] >> /GrayImageDict << /QFactor 0.15 /HSamples [1 1 1 1] /VSamples [1 1 1 1] >> /JPEG2000GrayACSImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 30 >> /JPEG2000GrayImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 30 >> /AntiAliasMonoImages false /CropMonoImages true /MonoImageMinResolution 599 /MonoImageMinResolutionPolicy /Warning /DownsampleMonoImages true /MonoImageDownsampleType /Bicubic /MonoImageResolution 600 /MonoImageDepth -1 /MonoImageDownsampleThreshold 1.50000 /EncodeMonoImages true /MonoImageFilter /CCITTFaxEncode /MonoImageDict << /K -1 >> /AllowPSXObjects false /CheckCompliance [ /None ] /PDFX1aCheck false /PDFX3Check false /PDFXCompliantPDFOnly false /PDFXNoTrimBoxError true /PDFXTrimBoxToMediaBoxOffset [ 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 ] /PDFXSetBleedBoxToMediaBox true /PDFXBleedBoxToTrimBoxOffset [ 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 ] /PDFXOutputIntentProfile (None) /PDFXOutputConditionIdentifier () /PDFXOutputCondition () /PDFXRegistryName () /PDFXTrapped /False /CreateJDFFile false /Description << /ARA /BGR /CHS /CHT /CZE /DAN /ESP /ETI /FRA /GRE /HEB /HRV (Za stvaranje Adobe PDF dokumenata najpogodnijih za visokokvalitetni ispis prije tiskanja koristite ove postavke. Stvoreni PDF dokumenti mogu se otvoriti Acrobat i Adobe Reader 5.0 i kasnijim verzijama.) /HUN /ITA /JPN /KOR /LTH /LVI /NLD (Gebruik deze instellingen om Adobe PDF-documenten te maken die zijn geoptimaliseerd voor prepress-afdrukken van hoge kwaliteit. De gemaakte PDF-documenten kunnen worden geopend met Acrobat en Adobe Reader 5.0 en hoger.) /NOR /POL /PTB /RUM /RUS /SKY /SLV /SUO /SVE /TUR /UKR /ENU (Use these settings to create Adobe PDF documents best suited for high-quality prepress printing. Created PDF documents can be opened with Acrobat and Adobe Reader 5.0 and later.) /DEU >> /Namespace [ (Adobe) (Common) (1.0) ] /OtherNamespaces [ << /AsReaderSpreads false /CropImagesToFrames true /ErrorControl /WarnAndContinue /FlattenerIgnoreSpreadOverrides false /IncludeGuidesGrids false /IncludeNonPrinting false /IncludeSlug false /Namespace [ (Adobe) (InDesign) (4.0) ] /OmitPlacedBitmaps false /OmitPlacedEPS false /OmitPlacedPDF false /SimulateOverprint /Legacy >> << /AddBleedMarks false /AddColorBars false /AddCropMarks false /AddPageInfo false /AddRegMarks false /ConvertColors /ConvertToCMYK /DestinationProfileName () /DestinationProfileSelector /DocumentCMYK /Downsample16BitImages true /FlattenerPreset << /PresetSelector /MediumResolution >> /FormElements false /GenerateStructure false /IncludeBookmarks false /IncludeHyperlinks false /IncludeInteractive false /IncludeLayers false /IncludeProfiles false /MultimediaHandling /UseObjectSettings /Namespace [ (Adobe) (CreativeSuite) (2.0) ] /PDFXOutputIntentProfileSelector /DocumentCMYK /PreserveEditing true /UntaggedCMYKHandling /LeaveUntagged /UntaggedRGBHandling /UseDocumentProfile /UseDocumentBleed false >> ] >> setdistillerparams << /HWResolution [2400 2400] /PageSize [595.276 841.890] >> setpagedevice work_grfbr2buobevfiwpgmch4xdlni ---- The Chief Justice as Executive: Judicial Conference Committee Appointments Cornell University Law School From the SelectedWorks of Dawn Chutkow 2014 The Chief Justice as Executive: Judicial Conference Committee Appointments Dawn Chutkow, Cornell University Law School Available at: https://works.bepress.com/dawn_chutkow/1/ http://www.lawschool.cornell.edu/ https://works.bepress.com/dawn_chutkow/ https://works.bepress.com/dawn_chutkow/1/ The Chief Justice as Executive JUDICIAL CONFERENCE COMMITTEE APPOINTMENTS D AW N M . C H U T K O W, Cornell University ABSTRACT This article is the first comprehensive empirical study of chief justice appointments to the Judicial Con- ference committees of the US Courts, entities with influence over substantive public and legal policy. Us- ing a newly created database of all judges appointed to serve on Judicial Conference committees between 1986 and 2012, the results indicate that a judge’s partisan alignment with the chief justice matters, as do personal characteristics such as race, experience on the bench, and court level. These results support claims that Judicial Conference committee selection, membership, and participation may present a vehicle for advancing the chief justice’s individual political and policy interests. The chief justice of the United States sits at not only the apex of a multileveled judicial decision-making body but also the apex of an increasingly vast administrative organiza- tion that influences federal courts and public policy. The federal judiciary commands an annual budget now in the billions and encompasses a workforce, both judicial and non- judicial, exceeding 30,000. The courts’ complex and sizable governmental face is repre- sented, if not controlled, by the chief justice and the judges he selects to serve on the Judicial Conference committees that set policy for the federal judiciary. The growth of the federal judiciary offers opportunities for political entrepreneurs, like the chief justice, to use the administrative structure and the incentives it creates to influence policy both in- ternal and external to the judiciary. These committees shape how the federal courts func- tion. As well, committees engage in interbranch contacts whose scope and nature include judicial position taking on matters of substantive legal policy. This article is the first com- prehensive empirical study of appointments to the Judicial Conference committees, the criteria by which a chief justice selects committee members and committee chairs, and My thanks to Theodore Eisenberg ð1947–2014Þ, Martin Wells, participants in the 2013 Cornell–Tel Aviv Empirical Legal Studies Conference, two anonymous reviewers, and the journal’s editorial board for helpful comments on earlier versions of the article. My thanks as well to Nicole Heise for her ex- cellent research assistance. Contact the author at dmc66@cornell.edu. Journal of Law and Courts (Fall 2014) © 2014 by the Law and Courts Organized Section of the American Political Science Association. All rights reserved. 2164-6570/2014/0202-0006$10.00 whether those selection criteria evidence an ideological component that suggests Judicial Conference committees can be used to forward the chief justice’s policy preferences in ways that move beyond general judicial administration. This article exploits a newly created database of all judges appointed by the chief justice to serve on Judicial Conference committees between 1986 and 2012. The results indicate that a judge’s partisan alignment with the chief justice matters for committee service. Personal characteristics such as race, experience on the bench, and court level also influence appointments. These results suggest that the avenues available to a chief justice for shaping legal policy extend beyond his role within the Court decision-making process. Control over the administrative side of the federal judiciary, through control over Judicial Conference committee selection, membership, and participation, may also be used to advance the chief justice’s interests in ways that are not ideologically neutral. JUDICIAL CONFERENCE COMMITTEES The Judicial Conference oversees the management of the federal court system aided by both the Administrative Office of the US Courts ðhereafter, “Administrative Office”Þ and the Federal Judicial Center. The Judicial Conference is chaired by the chief justice ðthe only Supreme Court justice who participatesÞ. It conducts the business of the federal courts through an organization of specialized committees whose membership is ap- pointed exclusively by the chief justice and drawn from the entire federal judiciary ðFish 1973; Wheeler 2003Þ. These committees engage in the substantive work of the Judicial Conference and act as gatekeepers with respect to the formulation of administrative ju- dicial policy ðFish 1973; Tacha 1995; Wheeler 2003Þ. Between 1986 and 2012, 25 stand- ing committees served the Judicial Conference. These committees advocate for certain legislative policy positions by providing Congress with assessments of proposed leg- islation’s impact on the federal courts, including substantive reviews of pending criminal laws, bankruptcy statutes, and the appropriate allocation of jurisdiction between the fed- eral and the state systems. They oversee and draft rules of procedure and evidence that govern the operation of federal civil, criminal, appellate, and bankruptcy litigation. Com- mittees prepare and present the federal judiciary’s budgetary requests to Congress, man- age nonjudicial staff and employment issues, identify additional judgeship needs, and report on court performance. Scholars studying this organizational structure are fairly uniform in their assessment that the Judicial Conference follows the conclusions and policy prescriptions reported out of the various committees ðFish 1973; Resnik 2000Þ. The Chief Justice’s Committee Control The chief justice has plenary power over the Judicial Conference committees’ structure and membership. He controls the number of committees, terms of service, chairs, num- ber and appointment of members, and committee jurisdiction ðJudicial Conference of the US Courts 1937, 1948, 1987; Administrative Office of the US Courts 2014Þ. Cur- 3 0 2 | J O U R N A L O F L A W A N D C O U R T S | FA L L 2 0 1 4 rently, active and senior Article III judges perform the bulk of committee service. Su- preme Court justices ðother than the chief justiceÞ do not serve in the Judicial Con- ference or on the standing committees, although they may serve on special committees. Appointment criteria are defined by the chief justice. Judges may express interest in service or recommend other judges for service by notifying the Administrative Office. Since 1987, committee service is limited to two 3-year terms per judge, with allowances for additional term extensions or committee chairperson extensions by the chief justice in “exceptional” cases ðJudicial Conference of the US Courts 1987, September 27, 60Þ. Prior Research, Organizational Structure, and Chief Justice Power It is well understood that administrative and organizational structures offer opportunities to influence policy outcomes and consolidate power. The chief justice’s unique position in the federal judiciary, and his potentially heightened ability to influence legal policy, pri- marily lies not in decision making where he is one vote of nine but rather in the accretion over time of administrative and customary powers. These include, most notably, opin- ion assignment, docket and case conference control, appointment power over special tribunals and panels, and—of interest here—appointments to the Judicial Conference committees ðFish 1984; Ruger 2006; George and Williams 2013Þ. The consolidation of institutional power in the office of the chief justice raises concerns, since the concentra- tion of this power is placed within the control of a single politically insulated actor ðCross and Lindquist 2006; Ruger 2006; Pfander 2013Þ. How the chief justice wields the appointment power remains largely unstudied from an empirical stand point. The few studies conducted are suggestive of strategic behavior, but with mixed results. Ruger ð2007Þ finds evidence of conservative appointments by Chief Justice Rehnquist to the Foreign Intelligence Surveillance Act Court but notes that these appointments do not appear out of step with the general leanings of the federal bench. Stancil ð2010Þ examines the power of Judicial Conference committees from a game theoretic perspective, noting their capacity to influence substantive law through rule-making procedures. Nixon ð2003Þ concludes that political ideology influences chief justice appointments to the Judicial Conference Executive Committee. Anecdotal evidence supports the contention that the chief justice uses Judicial Con- ference committee appointments in a strategic way, selecting judges who align with the chief justice’s political point of view and eschewing judges whose policies are too distant ðFish 1973; Resnik 1998Þ. Chief Justice Warren reportedly used the committee struc- ture as a means to orchestrate and bolster his positions before the Judicial Conference, as well as to reward policy allies ðFish 1973, 33–34, 268Þ. Chief Justice Hughes required personal preapproval of important committee reports before submitting them to the main body, which in turn reflexively followed the committee recommendations ð259Þ. More recently, then-senator Joseph Biden commented during a Senate Judiciary Com- mittee hearing on additional judgeships, “When it comes to playing politics and dol- Chief Justice as Executive | 3 0 3 ing out patronage, the Judicial Conference has no equal that I have seen before this committee.”1 Judicial Conference committee service provides value to the serving member. District court and special court judges fought hard to be included in both the conference and its committees ðFish 1973Þ. Federal judges have few opportunities to distinguish themselves ðPosner 1996Þ, their salary and tenure being uniform across district and appellate levels, respectively. Committee service that differentiates a judge from her peers and provides increased opportunity to interact with the executive and congressional branches may function as a kind of judicial patronage. Committees and Substantive Policy Apprehensions about an organized judiciary and the chief justice using the Judicial Con- ference to blur lines between administrative and political matters are not new, dating back to the initial authorization of the Judicial Conference by the Judiciary Act of 1922 ðPadelford 1932Þ. Many of these concerns focus on the potential for the judiciary to influence legislative outcomes and generally are of two kinds. First, the creation of vari- ous procedural rules for the federal judiciary, a task controlled by the related rules com- mittees of the Judicial Conference, may advance judicial self-interest, including policy preferences such as reductions in specific caseload types or litigation barriers aimed only at certain kinds of claimants ðRuger 2006; Stancil 2010; Pfander 2013Þ. Second, and relatedly, there is unease with the potential effects of systemized judicial interaction with Congress under the auspices of providing advice regarding pending legislation and its impact on the federal judiciary ðGeyh 1996, 2006; Cross and Lindquist 2006; Resnik 2010Þ. Both these points skirt a fine line between Congress’s need for relevant informa- tion regarding the judiciary’s experience with certain laws and issue-based advocacy that some scholars note create confounds for a judiciary that may also find some issues of re- lated legislation challenged in the courts ðResnik 2000, 2010; Ruger 2004, 2006Þ. In the 27 years covered by this study, Judicial Conference committee members ap- peared before or reported to Congress over 300 times on a regularized basis, including committee member testimony on pending legislation or other legislative matters.2 Less susceptible to definitive count are ongoing and equally regularized formal and informal contacts with congressional committees and members of Congress. The subject areas that fall under this umbrella are numerous and nontrivial. The Judicial Conference, for example, has long opposed mandatory minimum sentences for federal crimes, usually citing the need for greater judicial control over sentencing to alleviate inequitable and inconsistent outcomes ða factor that induced this type of legislationÞ and the costs of increased prison and supervised release populations. In keeping with this long-standing 1. Hearings on S.2027 and S.2648 before the Senate Committee on the Judiciary, 101st Cong., 2d sess. 308 ð1990Þ; cited in Nihan ð1995Þ. 2. Congressional Record, September 30, 1986, to December 31, 2012. 3 0 4 | J O U R N A L O F L A W A N D C O U R T S | FA L L 2 0 1 4 position, Judge Bell, chair of the Judicial Conference’s Criminal Law Committee, wrote Senator Leahy in 2012 advocating for the passage of the Justice Safety Valve Act of 2013, arguing that mandatory sentences “are wasteful of taxpayer dollars, produce unjust re- sults, are incompatible with the concept of guideline sentencing, and could undermine confidence in the judicial system” ðBell 2013, 2Þ. The official organs of the federal judiciary consistently oppose the creation of new federal rights ðJudicial Conference of the US Courts 1995; de Figueiredo and Tiller 1996; Posner 1996Þ or at the very least resist new federal rights not paired with substantial ðand often highly unlikelyÞ increases in judicial resources. In 2013, the conference took a strong position on pending immigration legislation expressing deep concerns about in- tolerable caseloads likely associated with increased enforcement mechanisms, broadened legalization and citizenship programs, and the expansion of the E-Verify program to man- date employer participation ðAdministrative Office of the US Courts 2013; Committee on the Judiciary 2013Þ.3 Immigration reform remains a contentious political issue at this writing, and no doubt legislative change will generate considerable litigation. To round out the list, the Judicial Conference took positions on such widely diver- gent legislative issues as domestic violence on Native American land ðSeptember 2012Þ, the Hague Convention ðMarch 2011Þ, probation officer search and seizure powers ðMarch 2008aÞ, prison litigation reform ðSeptember 2008bÞ, class actions ðSeptember 2007bÞ, wiretapping laws ðMarch 2007aÞ, restrictions on social security claims, diversity jurisdiction, the North American Free Trade Agreement, asbestos-related claims, habeas jurisdiction, medical privacy issues, the General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade, gov- ernmental taking of private property, and animal research ðAdministrative Office of the US Courts 1994, 2005; Nixon 2003Þ. Since so much public policy is either created or challenged in federal courts ðOlson 1991; Kagan 2001Þ, advocating restrictions on litigant access to the federal system may not be a policy-neutral endeavor ðResnik 1998, 2000, 2010; Stancil 2010Þ. Limitations on habeas petitions to federal courts, for exam- ple, affect prisoner rights litigation and federal review of state action by transferring more power to the state courts. Curtailed review of administrative actions in social security and health care serves to bolster the quasi-judicial power of agencies. The remainder of the article empirically examines chief justice selections to the Ju- dicial Conference committees, discusses the results, and then concludes. The chief jus- tice’s plenary control over committee appointments, his strategic use of other institutional powers to advance his preferences, and the anecdotal evidence all suggest that Judicial Conference committees provide another avenue for the chief justice to influence both the legal system and legal policy. 3. The bill, S.744, passed the Senate on June 27, 2013, with minor modifications, despite the judiciary’s concerns. Chief Justice as Executive | 3 0 5 DATA AND METHOD The research presented here employs a newly created database of all judges appointed to serve on Judicial Conference committees from all Article III judges, both active and senior status, serving on the federal bench from June 1, 1986, through December 31, 2012.4 The data span both Rehnquist’s and Robert’s terms as chief justice.5 Dependent Variables The variable of interest, Selected, records whether a judge was selected to serve on any Judicial Conference committee.6 As prior scholarship expresses concern over the im- pact Judicial Conference committees may have on substantive legal policy, Selected Law Committee represents selection to any of the nine committees ð“Law Committees”Þ whose domains involve procedural rules or federal court jurisdictional matters. Outside of the Budget and Spaces and Facilities committees, these nine Law Committees are among the most active before Congress.7 Service for multiple terms, or as a committee chair, increases opportunities to influence committee policy. In particular, when a judge is appointed to a third term and beyond, the chief justice expressly violates his own rule regarding the limits on committee service. Over Two Terms records judges selected to serve on the same committee for more than the two-term maximum articulated by the chief justice. Chair represents a judge’s selection as a committee chairperson. Law Chair represents a judge’s selection as chair for any one of the nine Law Committees. Selections were recorded as binary variables, taking the value of 1 if a judge is selected within a particular observation interval. The unit of analysis is at the individual judge level. For the time-series analyses, a separate observation was recorded for each judge at the end of each 12-month period of service on the federal bench. For example, a judge who serves the full time covered by the data set generates 27 observations, each representing a continuous 12-month interval. This allows for analysis of the chief justice’s selection process, controlling for the pool of 4. Data were acquired from the committee service records kept by the Administrative Office of the US Courts in Washington, DC. 5. Senior judges were included because their status does not preclude committee service. The focus is on aggregate chief justice behavior, so both Courts are considered together. For ancillary regression analyses, the data also were separated by chief justice term. However, observations on the Roberts Court covered approximately 7 years ðSeptember 2005–December 2012Þ, and power issues resulted in some individual chief justice models that could not differentiate from the null. Results from separate chief justice analyses with respect to committee and Law Committee selection are discussed. The remaining power-compromised model results are not reported, although they are available from the author. 6. Service on the Executive Committee was excluded, as its members may be drawn only from the Judicial Conference itself, a constraint not present in other committee selections. 7. The Law Committees are Administration of the Bankruptcy System, Criminal Law, Federal- State Jurisdiction, Rules, and the Rules Advisory Committees on Appellate Practice, Bankruptcy, Civil Procedure, Criminal Procedure, and Evidence. 3 0 6 | J O U R N A L O F L A W A N D C O U R T S | FA L L 2 0 1 4 judges available for committee selection during each interval observed. Once a judge was selected to serve on a committee, she was removed from the available selection pool un- til her 3-year term of service was completed or until she left the committee, whichever date was earliest.8 Upon death or retirement, a judge was removed permanently from the selection pool. Party Alignment To explore whether Judicial Conference committee appointments follow some kind of politically based preference, signaling a greater probability that selection operates as a mechanism for control over policy outcomes, each judge was assigned a partisan label ðRepublican or DemocratÞ on the basis of the party of her appointing president.9 Chief Justice Party is a dichotomous variable recorded as 1 if the judge was appointed by a Republican president, and thus is the same party of appointment as the chief justice.10 As a robustness check, more fine-grained measures of ideological preference were based on derivations of Poole and Rosenthal’s first-dimension Nominate Common Space Scores ðPoole and Rosenthal 1997; Poole 1998, 2005Þ.11 Appellate and district court judicial Nominate Common Space Scores were assigned according to the method developed by Giles, Hettinger, and Peppers ð2001Þ, using norms of senatorial courtesy to assign judges a Nominate Common Space Score derived from the scores of their home state senators. The chief justice’s judicial Nominate Common Space Score was calculated by the method described by Epstein et al. ð2007Þ in which preference points for each justice premised on changing voting patterns are transformed into Nominate Common Space Scores.12 These various Nominate Common Space Score calculations are referred to as “Common Space Scores,” throughout the remainder of the article. Biographical and Control Variables With the exception of case decisions and opinions, the federal courts’ impact on policy is filtered through other institutional actors ðCongress, the president, and the bureaucracyÞ. To explore whether the chief justice takes into account preference alignment between 8. In other words, if a judge is selected in 1990 but leaves committee service after 1 year, she is returned to the selection pool in 1991. 9. Party labels, as determined by a judge’s or justice’s appointing president prove to be a remarkably reliable measure of preference across a wide range of studies ðPinello 1999; Sisk and Heise 2005Þ. 10. Both Rehnquist and Roberts were appointed by Republican presidents—Rehnquist by Richard Nixon and then elevated by Ronald Reagan and Roberts by George W. Bush. 11. Ideological divides are structured primarily along the first dimension ðPoole and Rosenthal 1997Þ. All scores are multiplied by 10, so that the scores range from 210 to 10 in order to aid interpretation of the odds ratios coefficients. A 1 unit change in a coefficient corresponds to a 0.10 unit change in the actual Nominate Common Space Score. 12. Databases and documentation for judicial Nominate Common Space Scores are available at http://epstein.wustl.edu/research/JCS.html, May 2010 version. Chief Justice as Executive | 3 0 7 judges and the congressional committees with the most active federal court oversight, the variable House Judiciary is the absolute value of the distance between the individual judge’s Common Space Score and the House Judiciary Committee’s majority member median Common Space Score.13 Contact and experience with state-level elites, designed to capture a judge’s relationships with members of Congress from her state and hence potentially greater access that may benefit the judiciary, is represented by Any State, a dichotomous variable recorded as 1 for judges with prior professional experience at the state level in executive, legislative, judicial, or prosecutorial service. Similar contacts or experience within the federal system, which may represent special access to actors in the executive branch or members of Congress, are reflected in the variable Any Federal, which takes the value of 1 if the judge had prior service in either the federal legislative or executive branch, including agencies and the Department of Justice. Biographical variables were identified for each judge in the database to control for characteristics, unrelated to ideology, which may affect the chief justice’s decision to appoint a particular judge. Biographical data, including prior work experience, seniority, gender, and race, were derived from information reported by the Federal Judicial Center. Recent scholarship on collective decision making and the Court has noted a paucity of variation in background characteristics within the federal judiciary ðincluding race, gender, and occupational experience; Epstein, Knight, and Martin 2003Þ. The follow- ing variables explore whether chief justice committee selection is affected similarly. Ba- sic information on race and gender, standard controls for any population study, were included as dichotomous variables, with Female taking the value of 1 if a judge is female and Nonwhite recorded as 1 if the judge is a minority ðall nonwhite judgesÞ. In addition, controls for occupational backgrounds were included. Business takes the value of 1 if a judge was in the private sector ðexcluding law firms but including in-house legal coun- selÞ. Appellate Clerk, a dichotomous variable, identifies all judges who, after law school, clerked on a federal circuit court of appeals. Academic is coded 1 if the judge was affil- iated before appointment ðeither full-time or in a part-time adjunct capacityÞ with an institution of higher education.14 13. All models were analyzed using the House Judiciary full committee median distance as well as measures for Senate Judiciary distance ðmajority party and full committee medians derived in the same mannerÞ both jointly and separately. As the results were not meaningfully different in any of the alternate specifications, models are reported using House Judiciary distance only. 14. This variable does not differentiate between professors and adjuncts. Engagement with an academic institution can be reflected in a wide range of interactions, and the article operates from the assumption that these interactions may reflect a qualitative difference that affects selection odds between judges affiliated and not affiliated with the academy. Alternate regressions not reported included the separate dichotomous variables “Adjunct” and “Professor.” Neither variable rose to significance in any of the models, with the exception of Adjunct in the Chair Law ðselection 82% less likely, p 5 .03Þ and the Over Two Terms models ðselection 1.75 times more likely, p 5 .01Þ. The general lack of significance is likely due to the small number of observations for each variable. Professors in the selection pool each year ranged from 109 to 176, and the number of adjuncts ranged from 74 to 160. 3 0 8 | J O U R N A L O F L A W A N D C O U R T S | FA L L 2 0 1 4 An individual’s experience within the judicial system may also affect committee service, with the assumption that appointment decisions should favor judges who are familiar with the federal judiciary’s administrative operations. Judicial experience on the bench was calculated from a judge’s total federal judicial service in years at the end of each interval.15 To address collinearity with variables for seniority status ðdiscussed belowÞ and the likely nonlinear effect of experience due to its correlation with age, ex- perience on the bench was converted into three dichotomous variables. Low Experience is coded 1 if the judge falls in the bottom quartile of the judges available for selection in an interval. High Experience is coded 1 if a judge is within the top quartile of years on the bench. Middle Experience ð25%–75%Þ is the reference category. Stature within the federal judiciary may also matter to appointments. As the circuit courts sit between the federal district courts and Supreme Court in terms of workflow and importance, it may be easier for an appellate judge to differentiate herself and come to the attention of the chief justice, hence increasing selection odds. Whether a judge sits on the federal courts of appeals is represented by the dichotomous variable Appel- late Judge. Judges who have elected senior status ðsemiretirementÞ may have additional time for committee service or, due to age, may be less likely to be appointed. To control for these possibilities, Senior Status takes the value 1 in any given year for all judges des- ignated as occupying senior status. To account for the default rule that a judge may serve only a two-term maximum, the regressions control for two-term service with the vari- able Served Twice, which takes the value of 1 after the judge completes a second term of committee service. Descriptive Statistics Of the 2,015 eligible judges, 842 ð42%Þ served on one or more of the identified Judi- cial Conference committees, and 297 ð15%Þ served on one of the nine Law Commit- tees. Multiple service terms are the norm, with 166 ð20%Þ of the 842 selected judges serving only one term,16 and 676 ð80%Þ serving at least two terms. However, service beyond the two-term limit was less common, with only 310 ð37%Þ judges serving three or more terms, a total that represents only 15% of the eligible judicial pool. Multiple committee service is observed in 225 ð27%Þ of the judges serving. Most of this service is not consecutive, with 138 ð61%Þ of second committee service taking place an average of 6 years after the completion of initial service. Looking at only consecutive committee service ðcompletion of a term on one committee and then immediate ap- pointment to a second committeeÞ, we observe that 13 of the 24 committees studied saw roughly the same number of judges switch into a particular committee as switch out of that committee.17 Of the remaining 11 committees, differentials between judges 15. For elevated judges, service begins at the first appointment to any federal bench. 16. This number is likely smaller; 66 of these judges cannot be observed past their first term of service, as they were appointed in 2010 or later. 17. The Executive Committee is excluded due to its limitations on selection and service. Chief Justice as Executive | 3 0 9 switching into and out of committees may be suggestive of between-committee service variability, but the numbers are simply too small to provide reliable trends.18 As an initial matter, it appears that party affiliation affects committee selection and composition. For each year 1986–2012, figure 1 compares the percentage of Demo- cratic judge committee appointments, Republican judge committee appointments, and the overall percentage of Republican judges in the available judicial pool. In 18 of the 27 years studied, the percentage of Republican judges appointed to committees exceeds ðoften by a considerable marginÞ both the percentage of Democratic commit- tee appointments as well as the overall percentage of Republicans available for commit- tee service. For example, in 1991, 83% of committee appointments went to Republican judges, although Republicans comprised 63% of the available judiciary. In 2012, appointments were 70% Republican, drawn from a 54% Republican judicial pool. In only three years, 2004, 2006, and 2007, do Democratic appointments exceed Repub- lican appointments. The apparent dominance of Republican judges also emerges as the analysis moves from yearly appointment patterns to the composition of key influential positions within the committee system. Figure 2 presents the percentage of Republican judges within the full judiciary pool ð54%Þ, selected to any committee ð61%Þ, selected to a Law Com- mittee ð66%Þ, selected as committee chairs ð67%Þ, and serving beyond the two-term maximum prescribed by the chief justice ð64%Þ. Some additional judicial characteristics warrant note. Stature, and perhaps familiar- ity to the chief justice, as represented by circuit court judges, also appears salient. Ap- pellate judges are represented in proportionately higher numbers in both committee and chair service than in the general Article III population ðfig. 2Þ. Appellate judges comprise 21% of the overall judicial pool but make up 27% of the selected judges, 30% of the Law Committee selections, 31% of those serving over two terms, and 36% of the committee chair selections.19 Figure 2 also shows that judges from racial minorities appear to be underrepresented in all facets of committee service. Nonwhite judges rep- resent 15% of the general population but only 12% of committee member selections and 10% of Law Committee member selections. Of those selected to serve over two terms, 9% are nonwhite, and of committee chairs, 5% are minorities. Empirical Methodology To further examine the effect of partisan alignment on the odds of committee selection, the data were analyzed using cross-sectional time-series maximum likelihood models, 18. For example, six judges switched out of and no judges switched into the Committee on Court Administration and Case Management. Conversely, nine judges switched into the Committee on Information Technology, and only one judge switched out. 19. These numbers include 57 judges who appear in both appellate and district court categories during the time span of the study, due to their elevation from the district to the appellate court bench. The proportion treats these overlapping judges as serving at the appellate level. 3 1 0 | J O U R N A L O F L A W A N D C O U R T S | FA L L 2 0 1 4 the appropriate method for longitudinal analyses of dichotomous dependent variables derived from data that cover a changing population observed annually. In particular, because fewer judges receive committee appointments than judges who are not ap- pointed in any given year ðselection percentages in the majority of years studied range between 2% and 9%Þ, the analyses use random-effects complementary log-log ðcloglogÞ models, designed to address estimation problems caused by the left skew ðdue to an overabundance of zeros, or noneventsÞ.20 A series of models analyze the individual judge-level characteristics that affect a judge’s odds of being selected to any committee, a Law Committee, a committee chair, a Law Committee chair, or appointment beyond the stated two-term maximum.21 Figure 1. Judicial conference committee selections ðby party affiliationÞ compared to full Article III party composition, 1986–2012. R 5 Republican; D 5 Democrat. 20. Results are reported in exponentiated coefficients. Values above 1 indicate an increase in the odds of selection; values below 1, a decrease. For example, a coefficient of 1.5 represents a 50% increase in the odds of selection. A coefficient of 0.50 represents a 50% decrease in selection odds. 21. Additional analyses, not reported here, look at the Rehnquist and Roberts appointments separately with respect to Selected and Selected Law Committee. The main effect with respect to party alignment remains the same for these separate models and is discussed further in the results section. Separate analyses with respect to Chair, Chair Law, and Over Two Terms were unstable due to the rarity of such selections when the data are divided. Out of 28,275 observations, the data contain 240 Chair appointments ðand 153 individuals serving; 189 by Rehnquist and 51 by RobertsÞ and 82 Chair Law appointments ð68 by Rehnquist and 14 by RobertsÞ, and of the 547 times an appointment was Over Two Terms, 307 were appointed by Rehnquist and 240 by Roberts. Chief Justice as Executive | 3 1 1 The regression equation is as follows: Outcomeijt 5 b0a 1 b1Chief JusticePartyit 1 b2Demographicit 1 b3Statusit 1 b4Backgroundit 1 b5PoliticalAdvantageit 1 b6TimeBenchit 1 b7ServedTwiceit 1 εit; where i indexes the individual judge and t indexes the year of selection. Outcome is the variable of interest. In the Selected model, outcome equals 1 when a judge is selected to any committee. In the Selected Law model, Outcome equals 1 when a judge is selected to a Law Committee—any of the nine committees whose jurisdiction encompasses ac- cess to the federal judiciary or changes to legal rules ðeither procedural or substantiveÞ.22 Multiple service patterns are examined in the Over Two Terms model, where Out- come equals 1 if a judge is selected to a committee and that selection represents the third ðor greaterÞ term of service. To examine service as a committee chair, in Chair and Chair Law models Outcome equals 1 if a judge is selected to chair a committee or Law Committee. Finally, controls are included for demographic information, judicial status, background experience, potential political advantage, time on the bench, and, given the two-term service rule, a control for whether a judge has already served the maximum number of terms ðServed TwiceÞ.23 The main coefficient of interest b1 expresses the Figure 2. Descriptive statistics: Characteristics of all judges, selected judges, law committee judges, over two terms judges, and chairs, 1986–2012. 22. Administration of the Bankruptcy System, Criminal Law, Federal-State Jurisdiction, Rules, and the Rules Advisory Committees on Appellate Practice, Bankruptcy, Civil Procedure, Criminal Procedure, and Evidence. 23. Served Twice is not used in the Over Two Terms model because of lack of variance. 3 1 2 | J O U R N A L O F L A W A N D C O U R T S | FA L L 2 0 1 4 increase or decrease in the Outcome odds if a judge is in the same party as the chief justice. All regressions also were conducted by replacing party affiliation ðChief Justice PartyÞ with the Common Space Score distance ðin absolute termsÞ between a judge and the chief justice. The substantive results do not vary from those reported below, with decreased judge–chief justice distance evidencing the same effect on selection as being a Republican appointee ðand therefore aligned with the chief justiceÞ.24 This is not surprising on several levels. First, party of appointment correlates strongly with ju- dicial Common Space Scores. Second, judicial Common Space Scores for appellate and district judges are not derived independently from judicial case votes but are as- signed on the basis of home state senators’ Common Space Scores and as such may represent no more granular a measure than party of appointment. Finally, the chief justice appoints, on average, 76 judges each year to various Judicial Conference com- mittees. It may well be the case that from an appointer’s perspective, party is a reliable and easily used heuristic. RESULTS AND DISCUSSION The regression results are consistent with the descriptive statistics and offer robust sup- port for the proposition that party alignment with the chief justice matters for selection to Judicial Conference committees and positions of influence within that system. Being a Republican appointee, and the same party as the chief justice, significantly increases appointment odds in every model ðtable 1Þ. Odds of being selected to any committee increase by about 73% for Republican judges, and the odds of selection to a Law Com- mittee more than double. Republicans judges are 58% more likely to be committee chairs and almost three times as likely to chair a Law Committee. Finally, Republican appointees are 74% more likely to remain on committees beyond the two-term max- imum, as compared to Democratic appointees. Other Variables of Interest In addition to the salience of party, a number of the other variables exhibit a consis- tent relationship to a judge’s appointment odds and are worthy of note. Figure 3 pre- sents these results graphically, with the variables on the X-axis and odds ratios on the Y-axis. The horizontal dashes indicate the odds-ratio coefficient for a particular vari- able, and the vertical lines denote the 95% confidence interval. An odds ratio of 1 rep- resents the null, and this grid line is highlighted. This figure demonstrates a fairly uniform pattern across the five models, with roughly the same groups of variables in- creasing and decreasing the likelihood of appointment. 24. Regression results are not reported but available on request from the author. Chief Justice as Executive | 3 1 3 Violation of the Two-Term Service Rule As was expected, after a judge serves her two-term maximum ðServed TwiceÞ, she is significantly less likely to be appointed to the same or another committee. Accordingly, Served Twice is below the null grid line in both the Selection and Law Selection models, representing a reduction in selection odds of roughly 80% ðtable 1; figs. 3A and 3BÞ. However, the model for multiple-year service ðOver Two Terms; table 1; fig. 3CÞ in- Table 1. Maximum Likelihood Models for Judicial Conference Appointments to a Committee, Law Committee, Chair, Law Chair, or over Two-Term Maximum, 1986–2012 Selected Selected Law Over Two Terms Chair Chair Law Chief justice party 1.73** 2.48** 1.74** 1.58* 2.71** ð.20Þ ð.54Þ ð.29Þ ð.34Þ ð1.04Þ House judiciary 1.00 1.01 .99 1.01 .97 ð.01Þ ð.01Þ ð.01Þ ð.02Þ ð.04Þ Female 1.61** 1.43 2.01** 1.50 1.15 ð.24Þ ð.38Þ ð.42Þ ð.37Þ ð.50Þ Nonwhite .61** .48* .64 .32** .30 ð.10Þ ð.15Þ ð.16Þ ð.13Þ ð.22Þ Senior status .39** .25** .58** .34** .29** ð.04Þ ð.05Þ ð.08Þ ð.07Þ ð.11Þ Appellate judge 1.83** 1.98** 1.99** 1.81** 2.46** ð.21Þ ð.41Þ ð.33Þ ð.37Þ ð.82Þ Business .63* .83 .73 .43 .29 ð.13Þ ð.31Þ ð.22Þ ð.20Þ ð.25Þ Academic 1.50** 2.02** 1.49* .92 .98 ð.19Þ ð.46Þ ð.27Þ ð.21Þ ð.37Þ Appellate clerk 1.93** 3.30** 2.44** 1.74 2.65 ð.44Þ ð1.22Þ ð.75Þ ð.60Þ ð1.41Þ Any state .78* .87 .61** .56** .71 ð.09Þ ð.18Þ ð.10Þ ð.11Þ ð.23Þ Any federal 1.25* 1.01 1.20 .98 .69 ð.14Þ ð.21Þ ð.19Þ ð.20Þ ð.24Þ Served twice .18** .14** . . . 4.13** 2.36** ð.02Þ ð.02Þ ð.74Þ ð.68Þ Low experience .20** .20** .05** .30** .15** ð.02Þ ð.03Þ ð.01Þ ð.08Þ ð.08Þ High experience .41** .28** .73* .28** .14** ð.05Þ ð.07Þ ð.11Þ ð.08Þ ð.08Þ Constant .06** .003** .01** .003** .0005** ð.01Þ ð.001Þ ð.001Þ ð.001Þ ð.0003Þ Wald x2 954.40** 348.20** 254.49** 235.84** 85.73** x2 925.01** 630.37** 404.83** 137.76** 48.23** Source.—Judicial Conference Committee data set, 2012. Note.—Binomial maximum likelihood models fitted with complementary log log function in Stata12. Exponen- tiated coefficients. Served twice is not included in the Over Two Terms model due to lack of variation. N 5 28,275. * p < .05. ** p < .01. 3 1 4 | J O U R N A L O F L A W A N D C O U R T S | FA L L 2 0 1 4 dicates that Republican judges are far more likely ð74%Þ than their Democratic counter- parts to serve beyond the two-term maximum. And when it comes to the selection of chairs, either to any committee or to a Law Committee, having served twice increases the odds of appointment by two- to fourfold ðChair, Chair Law; table 1; figs. 3D and 3EÞ. This suggests that the chief justice selects a group of judges for multiyear service, in con- travention to the two-term limit, and then favors them for selection to positions of con- trol within the committees. The question remains whether being a Republican appointee makes it more likely that a particular judge will receive multiple term appointments and will be more likely to serve as a committee chair. To explore this question further, an additional regression was conducted with the dependent variable coded 1 for all judges who already served two terms and in any subsequent year were appointed as committee chairs. Again, partisan alignment with the chief justice matters, almost doubling the odds that a judge will serve multiple terms and act as a committee chair ðtable 2Þ. Positive Impact on Selection Appellate judges, like Republican judges, have significantly higher selection odds. As compared to their district court counterparts, judges on the courts of appeals are 83% more likely to be selected to any committee and 81% more likely to serve as a committee chair, are roughly twice as likely to be appointed to a Law Committee or multiple-year service, and are over two times more likely to chair a Law Committee. Republican ap- pointment and appellate court status are the only two variables significantly positive across all five models. Academics and former appellate clerks also are more likely to serve on committees and to serve beyond the two-term maximum, lending some credence to assertions that the lack of occupational diversity on the bench extends to committee service. However, this increase in odds does not uniformly apply to committee leader- ship positions ðtable 1; figs. 3D and 3EÞ. Negative Impact on Selection Control variables for experience all behaved as expected. The chief justice is more likely to appoint judges from the midrange of experience on the bench. Low Experience and High Experience reduced the odds of appointment anywhere from roughly 30% to 95%, depending on the model, and were consistently negative across all five models. Senior status also consistently and significantly reduced appointment odds by over half in most models. Being a racial minority reduces a judge’s odds of committee service in three of the five models.25 Minority judges are 39% less likely to be selected to any committee, 52% less 25. The exceptions are the multiple term ðOver Two TermsÞ and Chair Law models, where Nonwhite did not rise to the level of significance, although the coefficients are below 1. Chief Justice as Executive | 3 1 5 likely to serve on Law Committees, and 68% less likely to act as committee chairs. It is possible that this is a function of the relative paucity in terms of both raw numbers and time on the bench for minority judges during many of the years studied, which reflects the variation in minority appointments during different presidential terms.26 It was not until 1997 that the percentage of minority judges in the High Experience category con- Figure 3. A, Selected to any committee; B, selected to a Law Committee; C, selected over two terms. 26. For example, newly appointed minority judges declined in 2000–2008. 3 1 6 | J O U R N A L O F L A W A N D C O U R T S | FA L L 2 0 1 4 sistently moved out of the single digits. Given this paucity, time on the bench and mi- nority status may interact in ways that dampen appointment ðor willingness to serveÞ. For example, minority judges at various stages of their judicial careers may find public and other external ðnonjudicialÞ demands on their time particularly acute, and these de- mands may supplant time available for committee service. All regressions were rerun using interaction terms to determine whether the odds of committee service differed for minority judges with differing levels of experience on the bench ðcoded 1 if a judge was both a minority and High, Middle, or Low Experience, Figure 3 ðContinuedÞ. D, Selected chair; E, selected law chair Chief Justice as Executive | 3 1 7 respectivelyÞ.27 The results show that, while race remains salient as an independent ef- fect, and experience also remains independently significant, more experienced minority judges are more likely to serve on committees and to serve over two terms in contraven- tion to the overall impact of long-term experience, which diminishes service odds for the selection pool ðtable 3Þ.28 While caution should be used due to analytic power issues associated with such a small number of positive observations, the ancillary regressions do support the theory that race and time on the bench matter for committee service in ways that differ from the nonminority population. Political Connections While the chief justice appears to take party into account when selecting committee members and chairs, there was mixed and contrary evidence that a judge’s possible po- litical connections make committee selection more likely. Prior experience in federal government ðAny FederalÞ increased selection odds by about 25% for any committee 27. The reference category was Middle Experience, with the exception of the Middle Experience model, where the reference category was Low Experience. 28. Nonwhite � Low Experience did not rise to significance. Nonwhite � Middle Experience judges were 30% less likely to serve than their Low Experience counterparts. The small number of observations for minority judges in the Selected Law, Chair, and Chair Law models precluded analysis. Table 2. Maximum Likelihood Model for Judicial Conference Appointment as Chair after Two-Term Maximum Service, 1986–2012 Odds Ratio SE Chief justice party 1.84* .54 House judiciary 1.02 .03 Female 2.35* .81 Nonwhite .29* .16 Senior status .42** .11 Appellate judge 2.28** .63 Business .45 .27 Academic 1.07 .33 Appellate clerk 2.83* 1.34 Any state .40** .11 Any federal 1.06 .30 Low experience .04** .02 High experience .49* .15 Constant .001** .0005 Wald x2 114.68** x2 178.56** Source.—Judicial Conference Committee data set, 2012. Note.—Odds ratios. Binomial maximum likelihood model fitted with com- plementary log log function in Stata12. Exponentiated coefficients. N 5 28,275. * p < .05. ** p < .01. 3 1 8 | J O U R N A L O F L A W A N D C O U R T S | FA L L 2 0 1 4 service but was not significant in the other four models. Prior state government ser- vice ðAny StateÞ decreased selection odds in three of the five models by between 22% and 44%. Chief justice committee selections show little preference for committee mem- bers with political ideologies similar to the key congressional committee. The Common Space Score distance between a judge and the House Judiciary Committee majority median ðHouse JudiciaryÞ failed to achieve significance in any model, with coefficients functionally equivalent to the null of one. Data Limitations The following issues arise regarding sample representativeness. Committee service is a function to some degree of judge self-selection via recommendations and judicial ex- pressions of interest funneled through the Administrative Office ðFish 1973; Adminis- trative Office of the US Courts 2014Þ. How strongly this affects the final committee composition is unstudied, as the Administrative Office data only contain committee ser- vice records, not requests to serve. Of the 2,015 judges observed, close to half engage in active committee service during the time periods studied. This number, however, is censored, as the study ends in 2012 and does not capture the full judicial life span of many judges present in the current data who may serve on committees after 2012. Whether self-selection is dispositive can be examined inferentially by looking at the number and tenure of judicial committee service ða substantial repeat cadre would tend Table 3. Nonwhite Interacted with High Experience: Maximum Likelihood Models for Judicial Conference Appointments to a Committee or over Two-Term Maximum, 1986–2012 Selected Over Two Terms Nonwhite � high experience 4.87** 5.65** ð1.50Þ ð2.45Þ Chief justice party 1.73** 1.74** ð.20Þ ð.29Þ Nonwhite .55** .48** ð.09Þ ð.13Þ High experience .35** .63** ð.04Þ ð.10Þ Model covariates Yes Yes Constant .06** .01** ð.01Þ ð.001Þ Wald x2 958.52** 266.26** x2 930.27** 404.30** Source.—Judicial Conference Committee data set, 2012. Note.—Odds ratios. Binomial maximum likelihood model fitted with complementary log log function in Stata12. Exponentiated coefficients. Interaction nonwhite � high experi- ence not included in Selected Law, Chair, and Chair Law models due to small numbers. N 5 28,275. ** p < .01. Chief Justice as Executive | 3 1 9 to support self-selection theoriesÞ. As an initial matter, the impact of any self-selection is moderated by existing term limits set by the chief justice that restrict committee service to two 3-year terms: 42% of the judicial pool engages in Judicial Conference committee service, yet only 15% of the judges observed serve beyond a second term. In addition, if judges self-select, there is no theoretical reason to expect Republican judges to volunteer for committee service in any greater or lesser degree than Democratic appointees ðunless they do so in response to an understood norm about service and party alignmentÞ. The data show a strong relationship between party and committee service. These findings suggest, at the very least, that if some form of self-selection is in effect, it operates in a manner that aligns judges and the chief justice along apparent partisan lines, an align- ment that is consistent with assertions that selection is designed to forward the chief justice’s policy preferences. Republican judges may volunteer to serve on committees more often than Democratic judges, but that choice could be due to the understanding that being Republican makes it more likely that the chief justice will select a judge for committee service. In any event, the end result is committee composition in which party alignment with the chief justice matters. In addition, the data do not include non–Article III members, the bulk of whom are private citizens. This is due to the practical impossibility of generating a full selection population of potential non–Article III committee members ðwhich would have to in- clude all eligible private citizensÞ and collecting the relevant demographic, political, and biographical information addressed in the current study. While there is no theoretical reason to believe that a chief justice would pursue a separate appointment strategy for non–Article III committee members, basic information about committee service pat- terns for this group allay some concern. Across all committees, Article III judges out- numbered private citizens, magistrates, or bankruptcy judges by an average of 56 per- centage points. In 14 of the 24 committees studied,29 Article III judges comprise 80% or more of the membership. Of the remaining 10 committees, five have Article III membership between 60% and 79%. Of the remaining five committees, three are be- tween 55% and 57% Article III judges ðadvisory committees on appellate rules, civil procedure, and criminal rulesÞ, and two ðbankruptcy rules and evidenceÞ were 43% and 41%, respectively. Nonetheless, as a robustness check, the Selected model was run us- ing two separate selection populations: ðaÞ committee selections where 80% or more came from the Article III judiciary ð“80% Group”Þ and ðbÞ the remaining nine com- mittee selections ð“Under 80% Group”Þ. Using either the 80% Group or the Under 80% Group, the results did not differ in any material respect from those presented here. Finally, because the data only include 7 years of Chief Justice Robert’s appointments, and because appointment to a Judicial Conference committee is a comparatively rare event, separate analyses of appointments by chief justice are reliable only at the broadest level: committee selection. The dynamic described in the main results, that being of the 29. The Executive Committee is excluded as its selection mechanism differs from the other committees: only existing Judicial Conference members are eligible for Executive Committee service. 3 2 0 | J O U R N A L O F L A W A N D C O U R T S | FA L L 2 0 1 4 same party as the chief justice enhances the overall probability of committee selection or selection to a Law Committee, remains when the data are divided by chief justice. However, more granular analyses separated by chief justice, including appointments over two terms, as chair, or as law chair are not reliable, particularly for Roberts, given the rarity of those actions and the reduction in observations when the data are split. Separate, more detailed analyses of each chief justice’s appointment behavior will have to await further data. CONCLUSION Partisan alignment between a judge and the chief justice is a significant factor in the chief justice’s Judicial Conference committee appointments. Regardless of the type of committee service, or its longevity, Republican judges have a distinct appointment ad- vantage over their Democratic counterparts. These findings are consistent with studies that find the chief justice uses his institutional powers ðopinion assignment, conference control, docket order, specialized court appointmentsÞ to influence case ðread policyÞ outcomes. The results support both the anecdotal evidence about Judicial Conference committees as well as early studies of the Judicial Conference Executive Committee that found ideological appointment behavior by the chief justice. Given the Judicial Con- ference committees’ role in crafting policy on behalf of the federal courts, these results suggest that the chief justice makes his selections with an eye toward populating the committees, and their leadership, with like-minded judges who in turn craft policies that comport with the chief justice’s preferences. The effect of party alignment on multiple-term service and chair appointments is particularly instructive. Positions of authority in a committee and longevity of service provide added opportunities to influence policy outcomes. Multiple-term appointments violate the chief justice’s rule on committee service limits. Yet the chief justice does ab- rogate this rule, and when he does so, it is more likely to be in favor of a Republican judge than a Democratic one. Appointments to positions of authority within the com- mittees follow the same pattern, with significantly higher odds of chairpersonship ad- hering to Republican judges. It is possible that partisan appointment behavior could serve purposes other than just influencing committee policy. The use of political party as a method of overcoming collective action problems is well studied in the context of congressional committees. A Republican chief justice could be rewarding Republican judges with committee assign- ments in order to promote, advance, and generate fidelity among these judges, with an eye toward some sort of internal party cohesion in the judiciary. The purpose of this unity building may be to reinforce the chief justice’s control over the federal judiciary, by appointing like-minded judges who support, or are incentivized to follow, the chief justice’s organizational goals ðas well as policy preferencesÞ. This is consistent with the history of the chief justice as an administrative entrepreneur, beginning with the im- plementation of the committee structure by William Howard Taft in the 1920s, ev- idencing a pattern of consolidated and centralized organizational control and expanded Chief Justice as Executive | 3 2 1 administrative autonomy for the federal courts ðFish 1984; Carpenter 2001; Crowe 2007Þ. The strong relationship between status as an appellate judge and committee service at all levels suggests that, in addition to populating committees ðand committee power structuresÞ with like-minded judges, the chief justice also may draw most from familiar judges. The appellate bench is not only smaller than that of the district court but also the bench through which most federal cases reach the Supreme Court ð28 U.S.C. §1254Þ. Three hundred fifty-seven appellate judges appeared in the judicial pool during the period studied, compared to 1,658 district court judges. In addition to appellate judges being fewer in number, the appeals process itself, with the circuit courts interposed be- tween the district courts and Supreme Court, may result in an increased likelihood that appellate judges are known to the chief justice. The role of familiarity is supported in- ferentially by the significance of judicial time on the bench, a variable designed to cap- ture appointments that favor some level of experience with the federal court system. New judges ðin the lower 25% of judicial experienceÞ are significantly less likely to serve in any committee capacity. In addition to less experience, these judges have had less time to distinguish themselves and become known within the judiciary ðand to the chief jus- ticeÞ. While judges with long careers on the bench ðin the top 25%Þ also are signifi- cantly less likely to be appointed as are senior judges, it may be that selection of this group is suppressed by service willingness or assessments based on age. A significant reduction in selection odds exists for minority judges. Interaction effects between race and time on the bench are suggestive. However, the nature and parameters of this effect are unclear, as is whether the salience of race persists across all committee types. This issue is worth additional consideration. As well, further study could examine whether appointment criteria, including experience, ideology, and self-selection, vary on a committee-by-committee basis. For example, over 90% of the subject pool engaged in prior legal practice. The contours of this professional experience, including practice-type categories ðe.g., litigation, corporate finance, employee benefitsÞ, and their effect on com- mittee service warrant study. Finally, the available data, while covering 27 years, only examine the selection be- havior of two chief justices. This is in part due to the nature of the records available from the Administrative Office. Additional empirical analyses of other chief justices’ com- mittee selection behavior are of interest, given this study’s results. As an initial matter, however, it is important that the office of the chief justice clearly affords the power and opportunity to use specific ideological or partisan criteria when appointing Judicial Conference committees’ members. REFERENCES Administrative Office of the US Courts. 1994. “Judicial Conference Adopts Principles for Health Care Reform.” Third Branch 26 ð8Þ: 1–2. 3 2 2 | J O U R N A L O F L A W A N D C O U R T S | FA L L 2 0 1 4 ———. 2005. Annual Report of the Director. Washington, DC: Administrative Office of the US Courts. http://www.uscourts.gov/uscourts/FederalCourts/AnnualReport/2005.pdf. ———. 2013. Annual Report of the Director. Washington, DC: Administrative Office of the US Courts. http://www.uscourts.gov/FederalCourts/UnderstandingtheFederalCourts /AdministrativeOffice/DirectorAnnualReport/annual-report-2013.aspx. ———. 2014. “Judicial Conference of the United States.” Administrative Office of the US Courts, Washington, DC. http://www.uscourts.gov/FederalCourts/JudicialConference.aspx. Bell, Robert Thomas. 2013. September 17 Letter to Patrick J. Leahy. Copy on file with the Senate Judiciary Committee. Administrative Office of the US Courts, Washington, DC. http://news .uscourts.gov/sites/default/files/Judge-Bell-Chairman-Leahy-mandatory-minimums.pdf. Carpenter, Daniel P. 2001. The Forging of Bureaucratic Autonomy: Reputations, Networks, and Policy Innovation in Executive Agencies, 1862–1928. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Committee on the Judiciary. 2013. Senate Report to Accompany S. 744 Border Security, Economic Op- portunity, and Immigration Modernization Act. S. Rep. No. 113-040. Washington, DC: Govern- ment Printing Office. http://www.gpo.gov/fdsys/pkg/CRPT-113srpt40/pdf/CRPT-113srpt40 .pdf. Cross, Frank B., and Stefanie Lindquist. 2006. “Doctrinal and Strategic Influences of the Chief Justice: The Decisional Significance of the Chief Justice.” University of Pennsylvania Law Review 154:1665–1707. Crowe, Justin. 2007. “The Forging of Judicial Autonomy: Political Entrepreneurship and the Re- forms of William Howard Taft.” Journal of Politics 69 ð1Þ: 73–87. de Figueiredo, John M., and Emerson H. Tiller. 1996. “Congressional Control of the Courts: A Theoretical and Empirical Analysis of Expansion of the Federal Judiciary.” Journal of Law and Economics 39:435–62. Epstein, Lee, Jack Knight, and Andrew D. Martin. 2003. “The Norm of Prior Judicial Experiences and Its Consequences for Career Diversity on the U.S. Supreme Court.” California Law Review 91 ð4Þ: 903–65. Epstein, Lee, Andrew D. Martin, Kevin M. Quinn, and Jeffrey A. Segal. 2007. “Ideological Drift among Supreme Court Justices: Who, When, and How Important?” Northwestern University Law Review 101:127–31. Fish, Peter G. 1973. The Politics of Federal Judicial Administration. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Uni- versity Press. ———. 1984. The Office of the Chief Justice. Charlottesville, VA: White Burkett Miller Center of Public Affairs. George, Tracey E., and Margaret S. Williams. 2013. “Who Will Manage Complex Civil Litigation? The Decision to Transfer and Consolidate Multidistrict Litigation.” Journal of Empirical Legal Studies 10 ð3Þ: 424–61. Geyh, Charles G. 1996. “Paradise Lost, Paradigm Found: Redefining the Judiciary’s Imperiled Role in Congress.” New York University Law Review 71:1165–1250. ———. 2006. When Courts and Congress Collide: The Struggle for Control of America’s Judicial System. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. Giles, Michael W., Virginia A. Hettinger, and Todd Peppers. 2001. “Picking Federal Judges: A Note on Policy and Partisan Selection Agendas.” Political Research Quarterly 54 ð3Þ: 623– 41. Judicial Conference of the US Courts. 1937. Judicial Conference Report of 1937. Washington, DC: Administrative Office of the US Courts. ———. 1948. Judicial Conference Report of 1948. Washington, DC: Administrative Office of the US Courts. Chief Justice as Executive | 3 2 3 ———. 1987. Judicial Conference Report of 1987. Washington, DC: Administrative Office of the US Courts. ———. 1995. Judicial Conference Report of 1995. Washington, DC: Administrative Office of the US Courts. ———. 2007a. Judicial Conference Report of March 13, 2007. Washington, DC: Administrative Office of the US Courts. http://www.uscourts.gov. ———. 2007b. Judicial Conference Report of September 18, 2007. Washington, DC: Administrative Office of the US Courts. http://www.uscourts.gov. ———. 2008a. Judicial Conference Report of March 11, 2008. Washington, DC: Administrative Office of the US Courts. http://www.uscourts.gov. ———. 2008b. Judicial Conference Report of September 16, 2008. Washington, DC: Administrative Office of the US Courts. http://www.uscourts.gov. ———. 2011. Judicial Conference Report of March 15, 2011. Washington, DC: Administrative Office of the US Courts. http://www.uscourts.gov. ———. 2012. Judicial Conference Report of September 11, 2012. Washington, DC: Administrative Office of the US Courts. http://www.uscourts.gov. Kagan, Robert A. 2001. Adversarial Legalism: The American Way of Law. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Nihan, Charles W. 1995. “A Study in Contrasts: The Ability of the Federal Judiciary to Change Its Adjudicative and Administrative Structures.” American University Law Review 44 (5): 1693– 1717. Nixon, David C. 2003. “Policy-Making by a Different Means: The Chief Justice’s Attempts to Shape Policy through the Judicial Conference of the United States.” Rationality and Society 15 ð3Þ: 345–60. Olson, Walter K. 1991. The Litigation Explosion: What Happened When America Unleashed the Lawsuit. New York: Truman Talley Books, Dutton. Padelford, Norman J. 1932. “The Federal Judicial Conference.” American Political Science Review 26 ð3Þ: 482–85. Pfander, James E. 2013. “The Chief Justice, the Appointment of Inferior Officers, and the ‘Court of Law’ Requirement.” Northwestern University Law Review 107 ð3Þ: 1125–80. Pinello, Daniel R. 1999. “Linking Party to Judicial Ideology in American Courts: A Meta-analysis.” Justice System Journal 20:219. Poole, Keith T. 1998. “Estimating a Basic Space from a Set of Issue Scales.” American Journal of Political Science 42:954–93. ———. 2005. “Common Space Scores, Congresses 75–108 ðMarch 9, 2005Þ.” Department of Political Science, University of Georgia. http://voteview.com/basic.htm. Poole, Keith T., and Howard Rosenthal. 1997. Congress: A Political-Economic History of Roll Call Voting. New York: Oxford University Press. Posner, Richard A. 1996. The Federal Courts: Challenge and Reform. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Resnik, Judith. 1998. “The Federal Courts and Congress: Additional Sources, Alternative Texts, and Altered Aspirations.” Georgetown Law Journal 86:2589–2636. ———. 2000. “The Programmatic Judiciary: Lobbying, Judging, and Invalidating the Violence against Women Act.” Southern California Law Review 74:269–75. ———. 2010. “Drafting, Lobbying, and Litigating VAWA: National, Local, and Transnational Interventions on Behalf of Women’s Equality.” Georgetown Journal of Gender and the Law 11:557–69. 3 2 4 | J O U R N A L O F L A W A N D C O U R T S | FA L L 2 0 1 4 Ruger, Theodore W. 2004. “The Judicial Appointment Power of the Chief Justice.” University of Pennsylvania Journal of Constitutional Law 7:341–427. ———. 2006. “The Chief Justice’s Special Authority and the Norms of Judicial Power.” Univer- sity of Pennsylvania Law Review 154:1551–74. ———. 2007. “Chief Justice Rehnquist’s Appointments to the FISA Court: An Empirical Per- spective.” Northwestern University Law Review 101 ð1Þ: 239–58. Sisk, Gregory C., and Michael Heise. 2005. “Judges and Ideology: Public and Academic Debates about Statistical Measures.” Northwestern University Law Review 99 ð2Þ: 743–804. Stancil, Paul J. 2010. “Close Enough for Government Work: The Committee Rulemaking Game.” Virginia Law Review 96 ð1Þ: 69–133. Tacha, Deaell R. 1995. “Judges and Legislators: Enhancing the Relationship.” American University Law Review 44:1537–59. Wheeler, Russell. 2003. A New Judge’s Introduction to Federal Judicial Administration. Washington, DC: Federal Judicial Center. Chief Justice as Executive | 3 2 5 Cornell University Law School From the SelectedWorks of Dawn Chutkow 2014 The Chief Justice as Executive: Judicial Conference Committee Appointments 201250 301..326 work_grjqtvrxybd55g74226l7hwqgm ---- Social welfare, justice and distribution Soc Choice Welf (2017) 49:415–421 DOI 10.1007/s00355-017-1088-y EDITORIAL Social welfare, justice and distribution An introduction to the special issue in honor of John Roemer Juan D. Moreno-Ternero1 · Roberto Veneziani2 Published online: 27 September 2017 © Springer-Verlag GmbH Germany 2017 1 Introduction It is our great pleasure to present this special issue in honor of John Roemer. The contributions collected here are meant as a homage to him and aim to reflect his many contributions to normative economics, political economy, distributive justice, and political philosophy over the last 4 decades. John Roemer received his A.B., summa cum laude, in Mathematics from Harvard College in 1966 and his Ph.D. degree in Economics from the University of California, Berkeley in 1974.1 His first appointment was at the University of California, Davis, whereheremainedfor26years(asanAssistantProfessorfrom1974to1978,Associate Professor from 1978 to 1981 and Professor from 1981 to 2000). In 2000, he joined Yale University where he is currently the Elizabeth S. and A. Varick Stout Professor of Political Science and Economics. He has served on the board of editors of several journals, including “Social Choice and Welfare” since 1990. He has been President of the Society for Social Choice and Welfare from 2010 to 2012. He is a Fellow of the Econometric Society and of the British Academy and has held a number of visiting appointments in various universities across the world. 1 He was suspended from Berkeley in 1968, due to participation and arrest in a demonstration and an occupation, lost his draft deferment, and taught mathematics in San Francisco secondary schools from 1969 to 1974, before being readmitted to Berkeley. B Juan D. Moreno-Ternero jdmoreno@upo.es Roberto Veneziani r.veneziani@qmul.ac.uk 1 Department of Economics, Universidad Pablo de Olavide, Sevilla, Spain 2 School of Economics and Finance, Queen Mary University of London, London, UK 123 http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1007/s00355-017-1088-y&domain=pdf 416 J. D. Moreno-Ternero, R. Veneziani In the summer of 2015, a 2-day conference took place in London to celebrate John’s 70th birthday, and his intellectual contributions, and many of the papers presented at the conference are collected here. John Roemer’s research spans from Marxian Economic Theory to Climate Change andEquity,encompassingDistributiveJusticeandPoliticalPhilosophy,PoliticalEcon- omy, Public Ownership and Market Socialism, as well as Pure Game Theory, Social Choice and International Economics. The sixteen papers collected in this special issue provide a good illustration of the breadth and depth of John’s contributions. 2 Marxian Economic Theory John’s early years were mostly devoted to Marxian Economic Theory (e.g. Roemer 1977, 1980). John was one of the founders of the so-called “September Group” which comprised social scientists, historians, and philosophers, on the Left and predomi- nantly Marxists at the time, who were engaged in a common project: to re-phrase Marxist questions using modern language, and to address them with contemporary tools of social science and analytical philosophy.2 This was later to become known as analytical Marxism—one of the most prominent Marxist schools in the Anglo-Saxon world. Methodologically, John’s key contribution was to show that much of Marxian eco- nomics can be derived using modern concepts of equilibrium and optimization: the Marxist phenomena of crisis, exploitation, class and technical change, among others, can be conceptualized as equilibrium phenomena of economies with optimizing indi- viduals. John’s models made analytical Marxism a force to be reckoned with in the social sciences. Whatever one thinks of the interpretation of Marx’s economics offered there, Analytical Foundations of Marxian Economic Theory (Roemer 1981) remains a classic. Substantively, it is fair to say that John’s most original and lasting contribution to Marxian economics is his reformulation of the theory of exploitation and class (Roemer 1982a,b,c, 1988). First, he showed that, in the general equilibrium of a range of competitive economies, a robust relationship exists between (Marxian) exploitation and class, and between wealth and class (where class is defined not in terms of income, but in terms of relation to the labor process). Then, exploring the normative foundations of the concept of exploitation, he argued that exploitation’s injustice is a special case of injustice due to unequal ownership of productive assets. Two of the articles published in this special issue deal with these topics. In “Marx’s CapitalThroughtheLensofRoemer’sGeneralTheory(andVice-Versa)”,GilSkillman considers how Roemer’s theory of exploitation and class has engaged and reframed the historical materialist critique of capitalism initiated by Marx’s Capital project. In “Globalisation and Inequality in a Dynamic Economy: An Axiomatic Model of Unequal Exchange”, Roberto Veneziani and Naoki Yoshihara provide an axiomatic 2 The September Group has comprised, among others, Jon Elster, Adam Przeworski, Robert Brenner, Philippe van Parijs, Hillel Steiner, Erik Olin Wright, and especially, Gerald A. Cohen who has had a profound influence on John’s thought. 123 Social welfare, justice and distribution 417 analysis of Roemer’s theory of exploitation using the standard tools of social choice and extend the key insights of exploitation theory to a general dynamic model of the global economy. 3 Equality of opportunity The analysis of the theory of exploitation as the foundation of the Marxian condemna- tion of capitalism represented John’s entry point into the theory of distributive justice and normative economics, starting with Howe and Roemer (1981). He was led to political philosophy in an attempt to understand why Marx’s concept of exploitation diagnosed an instance of injustice. In 1993, John published his most cited paper to date, which contained the seed of his theory of equality of opportunity (Roemer 1993). Traditionally, equality of opportunity was understood as the absence of legal bar to access to education, to all positions and jobs, and the fact that all hiring was meritocratic. This traditional view was mostly challenged in political philosophy to additionally require compensating persons for a variety of circumstances whose distribution is morally arbitrary (e.g., Rawls 1971; Dworkin 1981a,b). Building on these philosophical contributions, John formalized a precise definition of equality of opportunity in an economic framework as an explicit method of selecting policies among a set of alternatives. In general, a policy can be reduced to a proposal for the allocation of some finite amount of resource across types of individuals sharing circumstances (i.e., aspects beyond the individual’s control that influence her status) as a function of the effort (i.e., aspects that also influence the individual’s status but over which she has at least some control) they invest. An equal-opportunity policy, with respect to an objective, should allocate the resource so that the degree to which an individual achieves the objective is a function only of her effort, and therefore independent of her circumstances. John’s theory remains extremely influential today3 and five papers in the special issue are related to it. In “Equality of Opportunity: How to encompass Fifty Shades of Luck”, Arnaud Lefranc and Alain Trannoy explore the issue of luck in the design of equal-opportunity policies. In “Inequality of income acquisition: The role of child- hood circumstances”, Paul Hufe, Andreas Peichl, John Roemer and Martin Ungerer estimate the effect of circumstances on income acquisition and find that the fraction of inequality attributable to circumstances is larger than in earlier empirical studies. In “Preferences for redistribution and social structure”, Erik Schokkaert and Tom Truyts investigate the consequences for redistributive preferences of homophilous reference group formation based on talent. In “Ex Post Inequality of Opportunity Comparisons”, Marc Fleurbaey, Vito Peragine and Xavier Ramos propose different criteria to rank income distributions according to an equality of opportunity approach. Finally, in “Gender and inequality of opportunity in Sweden”, Markus Jantti, Karin Hederos Eriksson and Lena Lindahl apply the theory to Sweden and find that gender is the 3 His 1998 book on the topic (Roemer 1998) has more than 2000 citations, according to Google Scholar. 123 418 J. D. Moreno-Ternero, R. Veneziani single most important circumstance in accounting for inequality in long-run income (and opportunities). 4 Distributive justice Although the theory of equality of opportunity represents one of John’s main con- tributions to normative economics, it is difficult to identify a topic in the theory of distributive justice that he has ignored. After more than 20 years, Theories of Dis- tributive Justice (Roemer 1996) remains a magisterial presentation of all of the main approaches and a deep, rigorous and original discussion of some of the key problems in distributive justice. But John has also analyzed issues of axiomatic bargaining (e.g., Fleurbaey and Roemer 2011), intergenerational justice (e.g., Roemer and Veneziani 2004), the veil of ignorance (e.g., Roemer 2002; Moreno-Ternero and Roemer 2008), fair allocation (Roemer 1986; Moreno-Ternero and Roemer 2006, 2012) and public ownership (Moulin and Roemer 1989; Roemer and Silvestre 1993). Three papers in the special issue deal with these topics. Two of them provide axiomatic analyses of distributive justice.4 In “The greatest unhappiness of the least number”, Walter Bossert and Kotaro Suzumura analyze a pure social choice problem in which they characterize the least-unhappiness principle, which is formally equivalent to the anti-plurality rule. So do Richard Brady and Chris Chambers in “A spatial analogue of May’s theorem”, where they establish that the geometric median satisfies Maskin monotonicity, anonymity, and neutrality (uniquely, for three agents) in a spatial model with Euclidean preferences. From a different vantage point, Woojin Lee and Younghoon Yoon, in “Capital in South Korea: 1966–2013”, deal with the dynamics of capital in South Korea, following Piketty’s successful research line, to which John has also paid close attention lately. 5 Kantian allocations More recently, John has started to investigate what an equilibrium would look like in an economy where people are motivated by more public or cooperative concerns, rather than being driven by self-interested utility-maximizing behavior. The starting point of his analysis is the observation of many instances of cooperative behavior, both in the lab and in the economy, contrary to the predictions of the standard maximizing models. One explanation of this behavior assumes that people are standard utility maximizers but are endowed with ‘altruistic preferences’. Yet, methodologically, this kind of explanation has an almost circular flavor. Substantively, in large economies one immediately faces a free-rider problem, as the welfare of others is a public good if an agent is an altruist. According to John, this suggests that cooperation, if it comes about, must involve some other optimization protocol which involves some kind of cooperative thinking. Specifically, John has recently proposed that cooperation may 4 Due to an unfortunate mistake in the editorial process, these two papers were both submitted to this special issue but appeared in a regular issue of the Journal (Social Choice and Welfare, 2016, Volume 47, Issue 1, pp. 127–139 and pp. 187–205). 123 Social welfare, justice and distribution 419 involve people engaging in ‘Kantian optimization’ (e.g., Roemer 2010, 2015) and choose the action that maximizes their payoff assuming that all other agents take the same action. This represents a fundamental departure from Nash behavior—and the related notion of Nash equilibrium—and may provide an alternative framework for thinking about individual behavior in a number of important economic settings. In “Fairness and the proportionality principle”, Alexander Cappelen and Bertil Tungodden deal with the problem of fair allocation and concentrate on a proportional rule somewhat similar to the one introduced by Roemer and Silvestre (1993), which is the intellectual forefather of Kantian equilibria. In “On seeing and being seen”, Jon Elster provides a thorough critical discussion of Kantian equilibria, and Kantian behavior, both from a broad philosophical perspective, focusing on Kant’s own theory, and from an empirical perspective, reconsidering some of John’s own (unpublished) empirical work. 6 Political economy John’s interest in inequality and distributive justice naturally led him to explore polit- ical competition. He became interested in political science because, as Lipset (1960) famously argued, elections are the democratic form of class struggle. In all advanced democracies, citizens organize their political competition through parties that compete in general elections. Recently, there has been a growing interest in providing formal models of political competition in general elections. The most commonly used models posit a unidimensional policy space and suppose that com- petition takes place between candidates whose sole motivation for running is to enjoy the power and privileges of holding office. Both assumptions, however, are quite unre- alistic. John’s work in this area has mostly been concerned with developing a theory of political competition on a multi-dimensional policy space and with policy-oriented candidates. The core of his theory, which builds around his celebrated concept of Party Unanimity Nash Equilibrium, or PUNE, is summarized in his 2001 book (Roe- mer 2001), but a range of applications have appeared in independent projects dealing with ambitious themes such as progressive income taxation (e.g., Roemer 1999), the role of democracy to foster equality (e.g., Roemer 2006), the role of racism in deter- mining political outcomes and redistribution (e.g., Lee et al. 2007), and the effect of caste on political competition and corruption in India (Acharya et al. 2015). In “Relinquinshing Power, Exploitation and Political Unemployement in Demo- cratic Organizations”, Carmen Beviá, Luis Corchón and Antonio Romero-Medina present a formal model to analyze the evolution of political power showing that, in some cases, rational agents who value the future may yield political power to another class, whereas in others exploitation is possible. In “The political choice of social long term care transfers when family gives time and money”, Philippe de Donder and Marie-Louise Leroux present a formal model of political choice for long term care which rationalizes an empirically observed fact: low income children provide informal help to their dependent parent while richer children provide financial help. 123 420 J. D. Moreno-Ternero, R. Veneziani In “Peripheral Diversity: Transfers versus Public Goods”, Klaus Desmet, Ignacio Ortuño and Shlomo Weber analyze the role of peripheral diversity in the problem of distribution. After micro-founding a new peripheral diversity index, they put forth a simple theory in which the cost of public goods increases with peripheral ethnolin- guistic diversity and tax compliance decreases with overall ethnolinguistic diversity. 7 Climate change In more recent years, John has concentrated on the pressing issue of climate change. Mostly in collaboration with Humberto Llavador and Joaquim Silvestre, he has aimed to provide a normative approach to global warming. There are two main issues in cli- mate justice. One concerns the just way to share the scarce global resource of a clean biosphere across generations. The other concerns the just way to share the respon- sibility of reducing greenhouse gas emissions between countries. It is now widely recognized that no attempt to solve the issues posed by climate change will succeed unless both aspects of the problem are taken into account. In the approach proposed by Llavador et al. (2015), a politically feasible solution to the international allocation problem requires that the dates at which the global South catches up to the global North in income per capita not be delayed from what they otherwise would have been. Subject to this constraint, the concept of sustainability proposed by them—which sig- nificantly departs from the predominant discounted utilitarianism—consists in finding an economic path that would maintain human welfare for all future generations, given environmental and technological constraints. They show that a sustainable path does exist in which the global South converges at the required speed, economic growth continues—albeit at a reduced rate—and global emissions of greenhouse gases stay below a reasonable limit. One paper in the special issue analyzes environmental issues and the notion of sustainability. In “Sustainable Growth”, Geir Asheim explores the view that a criterion of intergenerational equity serves to make choices according to ethical intuitions on a domain of relevant technological environments. Today, we celebrate John’s contributions in all of the above fields and hope that he will continue his research for many years to come. References Acharya A, Roemer J, Somanathan R (2015) Caste, corruption and political competition in India. Res Econ 69:336–352 Dworkin R (1981a) What is equality? Part 1: Equality of welfare. Philos Public Aff 10:185–246 Dworkin R (1981b) What is equality? Part 2: Equality of resources. Philos Public Aff 10:283–345 Fleurbaey M, Roemer JE (2011) Judicial precedent as a dynamic rationale for axiomatic bargaining theory. Theor Econ 6:289–310 Howe RE, Roemer JE (1981) Rawlsian justice as the core of a game. Am Econ Rev 71:880–895 Lee W, Roemer JE, Van der Straeten K (2007) Racism, xenophobia and distribution: multi-issue politics in advanced democracies. Harvard University Press and Russell Sage Foundation, Cambridge, MA Lipset SM (1960) Political man: the social bases of politics. Anchor Books, New York Llavador W, Roemer JE, Silvestre J (2015) Sustainability for a warming planet. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA 123 Social welfare, justice and distribution 421 Moreno-Ternero J, Roemer JE (2006) Impartiality, priority and solidarity in the theory of justice. Econo- metrica 74:1419–1427 Moreno-Ternero J, Roemer JE (2008) The veil of ignorance violates priority. Econ Philos 24:233–257 Moreno-Ternero J, Roemer JE (2012) A common ground for resource and welfare egalitarianism. Games Econ Behav 75:832–841 Moulin H, Roemer JE (1989) Public ownership of the external world and private ownership of self. J Polit Econ 97:347–367 Rawls J (1971) A theory of justice. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA Roemer JE (1977) Technical change and the tendency of the rate of profit to fall. J Econ Theory 16:403–424 Roemer JE (1980) A general equilibrium approach to Marxian economics. Econometrica 48:505–530 Roemer JE (1981) Analytical foundations of Marxian economic theory. Cambridge University Press, Cam- bridge, MA Roemer JE (1982a) Origins of exploitation and class: value theory of pre-capitalist economy. Econometrica 50:163–192 Roemer JE (1982b) Exploitation, alternatives and socialism. Econ J 92:87–107 Roemer JE (1982c) A general theory of exploitation and class. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA Roemer JE (1986) Equality of resources implies equality of welfare. Q J Econ 101:751–784 Roemer JE (1988) Free to lose. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA Roemer JE (1993) A pragmatic theory of responsibility for the egalitarian planner. Philos Public Aff 22:146– 166 Roemer JE (1996) Theories of distributive justice. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA Roemer JE (1998) Equality of opportunity. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA Roemer JE (1999) The democratic political economy of progressive income taxation. Econometrica 67:1–19 Roemer JE (2001) Political competition: theory and applications. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA Roemer JE (2002) Egalitarianism against the veil of ignorance. J Philos 99:167–184 Roemer JE (2006) Democracy, education, and equality. Econometric society monograph series. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Roemer JE (2010) Kantian equilibrium. Scand J Econ 112:1–24 Roemer JE (2015) Kantian optimization: a microfoundation for cooperation. J Public Econ 127:45–57 Roemer JE, Silvestre J (1993) The proportional solution for economies with both private and public own- ership. J Econ Theory 59:426–444 Roemer JE, Veneziani R (2004) What we owe our children, they their children. J Public Econ Theory 6:637–654 123 Social welfare, justice and distribution An introduction to the special issue in honor of John Roemer 1 Introduction 2 Marxian Economic Theory 3 Equality of opportunity 4 Distributive justice 5 Kantian allocations 6 Political economy 7 Climate change References work_grp6rqugk5fwvgwb3bvhtfqpya ---- Climate Justice and Human Rights Abstract: Climate change as well as climate policies can have adverse effects on the human rights of certain population groups – and can exacerbate situations of injustice. As it stands today, the human rights regime is not set to sufficiently address these situations of climate injustice. In this article, I suggest a systematization of the normative climate justice literature that can be used as an analytical framework to evaluate current developments in human rights law and policy, and their potential to diminish inter-national, intra-societal and inter- generational climate injustice. I argue that further advancing procedural and substantive human rights obligations and corresponding enforcement mechanisms constitute one important way of establishing climate justice practices. Moreover, I suggest that the normative climate justice literature can be fruitfully used in International Relations to evaluate policy developments at the intersection between climate change and other policy fields. “The law – human rights law […] – is not ready-made to deliver climate justice: it must evolve. A question that arises is whether it can.” 1 1. Introduction In the face of anthropogenic climate change, we have begun to re-think justice. New reflections on the temporal and spatial aspects of justice have gained meaning. 2 It becomes increasingly relevant to consider how just relations between state actors, societies and generations in the context of climate challenges can be construed. Who bears the responsibility for and who are the ‘recipients’ 3 of climate justice? What obligations does climate justice entail? Stephen Humphreys has argued that climate justice begins with the law 4 . Human rights law and commentaries by the respective treaty bodies are clear about identifying rights-holders, duty-bearers and obligations. Climate justice means to comply with the rights standards already agreed upon even if climatic impacts imply more far-reaching and costly implementation obligations than expected when fundamental human rights treaties were adopted and ratified. As it stands today, however, the human rights regime is not set to sufficiently address situations of climate injustice, even more so as climate-related challenges exacerbate already existing situations of injustice. 5 There are various debates on how human rights could further evolve to appropriately protect rights-holders that are affected by climate change and climate- Author(s), Climate justice and human rights, International Relations (32.3) pp. 275-295. Copyright © The Author 2018. Reprinted by permission of SAGE Publications. 2 related activities. Important examples for these debates could be observed in the run-up to the 2015 Paris Conference of the Parties (COP). By the end of 2014, the Special Procedures mandate-holders of the Human Rights Council, among others, the Special Rapporteur on the Human Right to Safe Drinking Water, the Special Rapporteur on Extreme Poverty and Human Rights, and the Special Rapporteur on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples, sent a letter to the State Parties of the United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change (UNFCCC) urging them to include human rights in the new climate agreement. 6 In the beginning of 2015, a group of 18 countries launched the ‘Geneva Pledge for Human Rights in Climate Action’ emphasizing the human rights implications of climate change and committing themselves to observing rights standards in climate-related action. 7 During the Paris negotiations, the academic Global Network for the Study of Human Rights and the Environment adopted a ‘Draft Declaration on Human Rights and Climate Change’. Its first principle declares that “Human rights and a profound commitment to climate justice are interdependent and indivisible”. 8 Also in the course of the negotiations, an inter-constituency alliance of non-state organizations (NGOs) persuaded states to institutionalize human rights in the climate agreement. This alliance comprised, among others, women and gender NGOs, youth NGOs as well as indigenous peoples’ organizations. The Paris Agreement adopted on 12 December 2015 now acknowledges in its preamble that state parties should: (…) when taking action to address climate change, respect, promote and consider their respective obligations on human rights, the right to health, the rights of indigenous peoples, local communities, migrants, children, persons with disabilities and people in vulnerable situations and the right to development, as well as gender equality, empowerment of women and intergenerational equity. 9 These preambulatory clauses 10 underline the close link between climate change, climate- relevant action, human rights and inter-generational justice. In this article, I want to delve deeper into understanding this link and the relationship between climate justice and human rights. I argue that an international human right to a clean and healthy environment is an important and comprehensive way to diminish climate injustice, understood as inter-national, inter-generational and intra-societal injustice, and therefore, it needs to be further developed. Human rights can be defined as principled ideas of protecting human beings and providing them with all necessary elements for a life in dignity. In this sense, they define the relationship between a state and its citizens but increasingly also regulate the behavior of private businesses and other non-state actors. 11 Human rights can be understood as a 3 normative concept (prescribing how this relationship should be) but also as an empirical concept (with concrete implementation measures pertinent to specific human rights treaties). Moreover, human rights can bridge the gap between normative climate justice claims and empirical climate justice practices 12 . Systematically analyzing claims brought forward in the normative climate justice scholarship against concrete developments in human rights law and policy helps to gain a better understanding of how climate injustice can be diminished through concrete human activities. These developments comprise procedural rights in climate policies to diminish intra-societal injustice, extraterritorial state obligations (ETOs) to diminish inter- national injustice and an international human right to a healthy environment. The latter is the most encompassing one, which would help to alleviate intra-societal, inter-national but also inter-generational injustice, and thus needs to be further institutionalized. It can be considered as emerging international law; it is anchored in several regional rights instruments and national constitutions but not yet fully institutionalized at the international level yet. This article shall help to grasp the linkages between scholarship on climate justice and policy development in the area of human rights. Its aim is to demonstrate that further advancing procedural and substantive human rights obligations and corresponding enforcement mechanisms constitutes an important way of developing just climate practices. Bringing these often disconnected debates from Law and Political Theory together is a fruitful endeavor for International Relations (IR) scholars interested in climate change, human rights, or the institutional interaction between both. By systematically analyzing the normative literature on climate justice I suggest an analytical framework that can be useful in IR to evaluate institutional and policy developments against claims formulated by Political Theorists and Philosophers on how to diminish climate injustices. This article is structured in the following way. First, I will disentangle the relationship between human rights and climate change. Second, I will systematize the literature on climate justice along three dimensions, inter-national, intra-societal and inter-generational injustice. In a third step, I will introduce developments on ETOs, procedural rights and an emerging human right to a healthy environment, and I will link these to the considerations on climate justice. Fourth, I will ask: What are the advantages and disadvantages of a human rights-based approach to climate justice? Finally, I will conclude by stating that strengthening further human rights developments, especially with a view to establishing a human right to a health environment, can make an important contribution to achieving more climate justice. 4 2. The Relationship between Climate Change and Human Rights The relationship between human rights and climate change is two-fold. One the one hand, the consequences of climate change have adverse effects on the enjoyment of human rights. And on the other hand, climate policies can lead to rights infringements of local communities, in particular indigenous peoples. In the face of climate change, all three dimensions of human rights, (1) civil and political rights, (2) economic, social and cultural rights but also (3) collective rights can be at risk. Climate impacts, including heat waves, floods, storms, droughts and exceptional weather events can – in extreme cases – threaten civil and political rights, like the right to life. It is bindingly anchored in the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR, 1966) and the Convention on the Rights of the Child (CRC, 1989). Sea level rise, temperature increase and changes in precipitation can also negatively affect the right to food, the right to water, the right to health and the right to adequate housing. 13 All of these social rights are part of the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (ICESCR, 1966). At the same time, they are also anchored in several core treaties of the UN Human Rights System, such as the 1979 Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against Women (CEDAW), the 1989 CRC or the 2006 Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities (CRPD). Cultural rights are also affected by the implications of climate change. Human rights arguments in this area are raised to strengthen international cooperation for adaptation and mitigation programs to protect world heritage from changed weather conditions, temperature increases, floods, storms and droughts. 14 The implications of climate change also affect collective rights, such as the right to self- determination. It is anchored in the ICESCR and the ICCPR, and reveals that peoples should be free to determine their political status but also their economic, social and cultural development. The right to self-determination can be threatened by rising sea levels and extreme weather events endangering the territorial existence of low-lying island states. It can also be at risk if indigenous peoples lose their traditional habitat as source of subsistence. When human beings have to abandon their state territory, their legal status and protection in the international system is unsettled. 15 Moreover, climate impacts adversely affect the collective right to a healthy environment. Such a right is not yet bindingly anchored in the international human rights system of the UN. Nevertheless, it has found entrance into regional conventions, such as the 1981 African Charter on Human and Peoples‘ Rights, the 2003 Protocol to the African Charter on Human 5 and Peoples’ Rights on the Rights of Women in Africa, the 2004 Arab Charter on Human Rights or the 1988 Additional Protocol to the American Convention on Human Rights. Thus, it can be considered to be a binding human right in several world regions. In addition to this, we can find judisprudence generated by different regional courts. The European Court of Human Rights, for instance, has made several rulings in favor of complainants in relation to environmental risks and pollution. It has also applied international environmental law principles and made reference to the decisions of other regional courts. In addition to that, there is a global trend to adopt environmental rights into national or federal constitutions. 16 Table one summarizes the adverse effects of climate change on human rights. 6 Table 1: The Adverse Effects of Climate Change on the Enjoyment of Human Rights 17 Climate Impact Human Impact Rights Affected Regions Concerned Sea Level Rise  Flooding  Sea surges  Erosion  Salination of land and water  Loss of land  Drowning, injury  Lack of clean water, disease  Damage to coastal infrastructure, homes and property  Loss of agricultural lands  Threat to tourism, lost beaches  Life (ICCPR, 6)  Self-determination (ICCPR, ICESCR, 1)  Health (ICESCR, 12)  Water (ICESCR 11,12)  Means of subsistence (ICESCR, 11)  Adequate housing (ICESCR, 11)  Culture (ICCPR, 27)  Property (UDHR, 17) Coastal (Low-lying) Areas Low-lying Island States Arctic Region Temperature Increase  Change in disease vectors  Coral bleaching  Impact on fisheries  Impact on agriculture  Spread of disease  Change in fisheries  Change in agriculture  Lost diversity  Threat to tourism  Life (ICCPR, 6)  Health (ICESCR, 12)  Means of subsistence (ICESCR, 11)  Adequate standard of living, food (ICESCR, 11) Sub-Saharan Africa Northern Africa South-Asia Latin America Middle East Extreme Weather Events  Higher intensity storms  Sea surges  Dislocation of populations  Contamination of water supply  Damage to agriculture (food crisis)  Psychological distress  Increased transmission of disease  Disruption of education  Damage to tourism  Property damage  Life (ICCPR, 6)  Health (ICESCR, 12)  Water (ICESCR, 11,12)  Means of subsistence (ICESCR, 11)  Adequate standard of living (ICESCR, 11)  Adequate housing (ICESCR, 11)  Education (ICESCR, 13)  Property (UDHR, 13) South-East Asia South Asia Caribbean Coastal Zones Island States Changes in Precipitation  Change in disease vectors  Erosion  Outbreak of disease  Depletion of agricultural soils  Life (ICCPR, 6)  Health (ICESCR, 12)  Means of subsistence (ICESCR, 11) Sub-Saharan Africa South-East Asia South Asia Latin America Based on data from: Marcos A. Orellana and Alyssa Johl, Climate Change and Human Rights: A Primer, (Washington: The Center for International Environmental Law, 2013) and supplemented with data from: OHCHR, Report. 7 On the other hand, there are empirical studies demonstrating that the implementation of climate policies can also lead to severe human rights violations. This concerns mitigation measures, such as Reducing Emissions from Deforestation and Forest Degradation (REDD+) programs, Clean Development Mechanism (CDM) projects 18 and Green Economy (GE) strategies 19 . It has been highlighted that in particular the transition process to altering energy patterns and a low-carbon economy can lead to human rights violations of local communities, indigenous peoples and (agro)-pastoral groups. 20 Rights infringements pertinent to climate policy implementation often occur in the context of conflicts around property, land and resources. This means that in very extreme cases, violations to the right to life have been reported, particularly when violent relocations were undertaken. 21 Furthermore, the right to property specified in Article 17 of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR), and the right to development, stipulated in the Declaration on the Right to Development, are often neglected. Similarly affected is the right to self-determination and the right to subsistence as well as related social rights to adequate housing, to food, to water and to health (ICESCR). Thus, one can conclude by stating that human rights are at risk due to severe climate impacts and can be infringed with climate policy implementation. 3. Dimensions of Climate Injustice There is a bulk of literature on climate justice, which is characterized by conceptual uncertainty. Despite this conceptual vagueness, considerations of climate justice have a few common denominators. They, first, stipulate a relational understanding of justice, i.e. the cognition that justice needs to be achieved between different actors. Therefore, it is relevant to establish the recipients (and burden-bearers) of justice and to establish which entities, i.e. individuals, groups, or countries, can raise claims against others. 22 Second, there is the perception that climate change consequences exacerbate already existing inequalities. 23 Environmental challenges can intensify economic and social disparities that might have their root causes elsewhere. Third, injustice in the context of climate change pertains to a situation, in which those who are the least responsible for greenhouse gas emissions are the ones that are most affected and most vulnerable to climate change consequences but have the fewest resources to adapt. 24 In this section, I aim at systematizing the literature on climate justice along several characterizing features, including recipients, burden-bearers, temporal aspects and normative 8 claims. Whereas some authors highlight justice concerns between states, i.e. inter-national injustice, others point to injustice between social groups, i.e. intra-societal injustice, or to an evolving injustice between today’s and future generations, i.e. inter-generational injustice 25 . Deriving from these varying understandings, respective normative claims to enhancing climate justice also differ considerably. Inter-national injustice emphasizes the historically grown relationship between developing and developed states 26 . The main concern is that developed countries have extensively utilized carbon-intensive industries to foster growth and developing countries (and emerging economies) shall not be able to do the same in the future. 27 Many developing countries are, in addition to that, confronted with the consequences of climate change most severely by facing extreme weather events, increasing floods and intensified droughts. Hence, there is an imbalance between the contribution to climate change (by developed states), harm resulting from that and lacking resources to adapt (of developing states). This dimension of injustice is historically grown; it has its roots in colonial times, has been reinforced with globalization processes and is reflected in current institutions. 28 Normative claims in inter-national injustice debates are that greenhouse gas emissions have to be reduced, adaptation and mitigation costs have to be more equally distributed and should relate to historic emission responsibilities (e.g. the polluter-pays-principle), energy and other consumption patterns need to alter, and fair institutions need to be created. 29 Some of these claims are also reflected in the “common but differentiated responsibilities” approach put forward in the 1992 UNFCCC. Harris, Chow and Karlsson, however, suggests to “[…] open up the traditionally closed box of ‘‘the state’’, [to] see that the real divide is not so much between developed and developing states as it is between affluent and poor people”. 30 Such intra-societal injustice concerns refer to the relationship among different groups between or within societies. Particular social groups are unequally exposed to the impacts of climate change to which they have contributed little. Environmental inequality “[…] reinforces and, at the same time reflects, other forms of hierarchy and exploitation along lines of class, race and gender” and may lead to situations of “double-discrimination”. 31 A report by the UN Human Rights Council identified women, children and indigenous peoples – but also the elderly and persons with disabilities – in developing countries to be particularly vulnerable to such challenges. 32 Questions of social injustices have also been taken up by climate justice movements. Concrete demands in this respect do not only refer to equity but also to participation on the basis of comprehensive information, access to judicial remedies and compensation. 33 Increasingly, claims for 9 procedural justice and rights are also brought forward in the context of climate policy implementation. In 2010, under pressure of the climate justice movement, procedural rights were institutionalized for the implementation of REDD+ programs at the COP in Cancun. 34 Finally, inter-generational justice pertains to the relationship between previous, current and future generations. Past and contemporary lifestyles, marked by the consumption of fossil fuels and high greenhouse gas emissions, have led to injustice toward future generations who might not be able to enjoy a clean and healthy environment. 35 The current generation of decision-makers needs to be held accountable for not imposing risks on future generations who are not responsible for greenhouse gas emissions. Demands in this respect comprise the establishment of environmental rights 36 , energy rights 37 but also rights-protecting institutions. 38 The idea behind such considerations is to introduce constitutional environmental human rights that oblige today’s representatives to adopt policies that take the interests of future generations into account fostering ways of indirect (and inter-generational) democratic representation. 39 All of these dimensions of injustice can also overlap, which means that future generations of certain societal groups in developing countries will be particularly exposed to these forms of injustice. Table two summarizes the dimensions of climate injustice. 10 Table 2: Dimensions of Climate Injustice Inter-national Injustice Intra-societal Injustice Inter-generational Injustice Character of injustice Imbalance between states’ responsibility and harm as well as resources to adapt Imbalance between societal groups’ responsibility and harm as well as resources to adapt Imbalance between past/current/future generations’ responsibility and harm as well as resources to adapt Recipients Developing states Societal groups, communities, individuals Future generations Burden- bearers Developed states Capable states, international community Capable states, international community Time range Historically grown Immediately Historically grown Immediately Historically grown Immediately In the future Claims Fair distribution of adaptation and mitigation costs, just institutions, compensation, reduction of greenhouse gas emissions Participation, information, transparency, access to judicial recourse procedures Transition to altering energy and consumption patterns and to a low- carbon, sustainable economy, codification of environmental rights Source: Own compilation on the basis of the literature cited. 4. Linking Climate Justice and Human Rights Debates In the following section, I aim to link normative claims stipulated in the climate justice literature with concrete developments in human rights debates and practices. Extraterritorial State Obligations Rights obligations beyond borders have been intensively discussed in human rights scholarship, particularly after the introduction of the 2011 Maastricht Principles on Extraterritorial State Obligations (ETOs). In the literature, ETOs are discussed as “transboundary” or “transnational obligations”. 40 They can be grasped as an obligation to international cooperation for realizing economic, social and cultural rights. 41 This obligation is derived from several provisions of the UN Charter, the UDHR, the ICESCR but also of more recent treaties like the CRC. 42 Article two of the ICESCR, for instance, states that: 11 Each State Party to the present Covenant undertakes to take steps, individually and through international assistance and co-operation, especially economic and technical, to the maximum of its available resources, with a view to achieving progressively the full realization of the rights recognized in the present Covenant […]. 43 This implies that member states are not only responsible for rights realization on their own state territory. In case they dispose of respective resources, they also assume responsibility for engaging into cooperative activities to progressively help implementing economic, social and cultural rights beyond their own territory. Next to territorial duties a state engages in when legally accepting a treaty, it also takes over extraterritorial obligations for the citizens of another state. The meaning of ETOs becomes increasingly important in the context of progressing de- nationalization and global challenges. In one of his reports, the UN Special Rapporteur on Human Rights and the Environment, clearly states that the obligation to international cooperation is particularly relevant with regard to “[…] global environmental threats to human rights, such as climate change”. 44 Moreover, the Maastricht Principles underscore that states have an obligation to avoid extraterritorial harm which is due to activities or omissions of other states or even non-state actors, such as private companies. ETOs, for instance, were clearly stated in the petition issued by Greenpeace South Asia with other NGOs requesting an investigation of the responsibility of major fossil fuel companies for human rights violations resulting from the impact of climate change in the Philippines. These so-called “carbon majors” include Chevron, Exxon, BP and Shell, among others. The Commission on Human Rights of the Philippines reacted to this petition and launched a first-ever investigation into the responsibility of these companies for the drastic climate-related rights impacts on its population in 2015. Public hearings will take place in this ground-breaking case in 2017. The petition clearly states that: “[…] extraterritoriality is not a bar to the Commission’s exercise of authority, considering the transboundary and global nature of climate change and other environmental problems and the associated human rights implications.” 45 ETOs entail the obligation to cooperate in order to realize economic, social and cultural rights even in the face of a changing climate. 46 This interpretation implies that there is a requirement to assist developing countries to bear the costs of adaptation and mitigation policies. 47 Thus, the concrete implementation measures in human rights treaties can be viewed as minimum standards that need to be achieved through adaptation and mitigation measures. The loss and 12 damage article of the 2013 Warsaw Agreement calls for cooperation and cost-sharing in building the resilience of communities and ecosystems, including risk assessment and management, as well as non-economic losses. Here again human rights serve as a guidepost – all cooperative action must be implemented with a view to protect basic human rights standards. Hence, conforming states would foster inter-national justice by providing assistance to those states that lack resources to shoulder costly action to respect, protect and fulfill human rights in the context of climate-related challenges. Even more so, states and international organizations (IOs) would further intra-societal justice by assisting those community members of a society that are most affected in their enjoyment of human rights. A further principle emphasized in the Maastricht recommendations is the right to informed participation in any matters affecting citizen’s rights. 48 This is an important claim in intra-societal justice considerations and constitutes a fundamental human rights principle. The significance of participation is also reflected in current debates on procedural obligations in environmental policy-making. Procedural Rights Procedural rights are of particular importance in environmental law. They establish a link between the state and civil society by fostering transparency and participation in environmental decision-making. 49 The most important procedural rights are the right to information, the right to participation and the right to justice, the latter usually meaning access to judicial and administrative recourse procedures. All of these rights are anchored in the 1948 UDHR and the 1966 ICCPR. Of far more influence in environmental matters, however, is the Convention on Access to Information, Public Participation in Decision-Making and Access to Justice in Environmental Matters, also known as the Aarhus Convention from 1998. Although it is only binding for ratifying states, it turned out to become the most relevant reference document when it comes to procedural rights in environmental matters. It has been drafted under strong NGO influence and focuses on establishing fair procedures for environmental regulations. 50 Scholars accentuate the human rights character of the Aarhus Convention as it confers rights to individuals and not to states, it strengthens procedural mechanisms, and comprises non-compliance procedures that are very similar to those of the human rights monitoring bodies. Thus, it can be interpreted as a door-opener for a human right to a healthy environment. 51 13 Although, procedural rights are well-established in environmental law already and relevant case law from the European Court of Human Rights (ECtHR), the Inter-American Court of Human Rights and the Committee on Civil and Political Rights, they have recently gained increasing meaning in climate policy-making. During the COP 2010 in Mexico, for instance, procedural criteria for the realization of REDD+ programs were added to the Cancún Agreements. These safeguards encompass respect for the knowledge and rights of indigenous peoples and local communities as formulated in the 2007 UN Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples as well as effective participation of all affected people and free prior informed consent (FPIC) as anchored in the 1989 ILO Indigenous and Tribal Peoples Convention. A number of NGOs lobby for a revision of the modalities and procedures of the CDM in line with these rights. 52 Infringements of local populations’ and indigenous peoples’ rights in relation to CDM project realization on the ground have continuously been a problem leading, for instance, to a landmark decision of Panama to withdraw the UN registration of its Barro Blanco hydroelectric dam project towards the end of 2016. 53 In the aftermath of COP 21 in Paris and during COP 22 in Marrakech procedural rights and institutional safeguards have also been discussed in relation to the newly established Sustainable Development Mechanism (SDM). 54 Prior to the Marrakech negotiations in 2016, the OHCHR has made a submission to the UNFCCC process emphasizing “the need for robust social and environmental safeguards consistent with international human rights norms and standards” to guarantee that the SDM clearly achieves its objectives without contributing to rights violations. 55 Besides their reflection in the UDHR, the ICCPR, the Rio Declaration and the Aarhus Convention, these procedural human rights obligations are further developed through the general comments of several treaty bodies and by the Special Rapporteurs as well as the ECtHR. 56 Procedural rights can strengthen adaptation policies through the inclusion of valuable local knowledge and participation in decision-making. Mitigation action is much more likely to be accepted if it is developed in line with FPIC and in a transparent and participatory way. Previously, we have seen a number of mitigation policies becoming unsustainable, such as Barro Blanco introduced above, because the exclusion of affected population groups leads to contestation and conflict. Regarding loss and damage, the use of local knowledge, transparency and access to information are necessary for disaster preparedness, as well as risk assessment and management. 14 The considerations made above show that procedural rights are particularly relevant when it comes to climate policy implementation. Even though there is empirical evidence that safeguards maybe difficult to adapt to local contexts or are not always carried out properly 57 , they have the potential to diminish intra-societal injustices. by providing information, ensuring transparency, including individuals and communities into environmental decision- making, granting access to the judiciary and administration and thus, enhancing participation opportunities. A Human Right to a Healthy Environment Although there is no substantial universal human right for the protection of the environment yet, its development is underway. 58 The human rights treaty bodies have in several commentaries recognized the link between a healthy environment and the rights to life, adequate housing, food, water and health. 59 Some scholars have made concrete suggestions on how a right to a healthy environment could be formulated. 60 Others point to the fact that it can be derived from other substantive rights affected in the context of environmental challenges. Regional bodies including the European Committee on Social Rights (ECSR), the IACHR and the African Commission on Human and Peoples’ Rights (ACHPR) have confirmed that environmental challenges can lead to infringements of economic, social and cultural rights like the right to health, water and food. 61 There are also several cases, in which the ECtHR has already enforced social rights with respect to environmental matters and demanded compensation even by private polluters. 62 Other indicators pointing to further developments in this respect are the establishment of environmental rights in regional human rights instruments and a large number of national constitutions. 63 Some scholars argue that due to the existence and application at the regional and national level, a right to a healthy environment is already consolidated. The UN Special Rapporteur on Human Rights and the Environment, John Knox, calls upon states to accept procedural but also substantive human rights obligations relating to the environment as existing or emerging international law. 64 One important argument underlining this emergence is closely related with ETOs and the duty to international cooperation stipulated in the ICESCR. Knox highlights the significance of cooperation in the face of climate change: “The most feasible basis for extending current environmental human rights jurisprudence to climate change is the duty to cooperate”. 65 Hence, one can understand the ICESCR as the basis for further developments in environmental human rights law and the 15 duty to cooperate anchored therein can pave the way to an emerging international human right to a healthy environment. In November 2017, Knox has held consultations on Draft Guidelines on Human Rights and the Environment. Article 9 of these guidelines outlines that every state has an obligation to establish and enforce a normative framework for a clean, healthy and sustainable environment, including: “effective legal and institutional mechanisms to regulate the activities of public and private actors in order to prevent, reduce and remedy environmental harm that interferes with the full enjoyment of human rights.” 66 By defining procedural and substantive obligation in relation to preventing, reducing, and remedying environmental harm that interferes with the enjoyment of human rights, Knox has made an important further step towards an international environmental human right through legal analysis and emerging practice. With the establishment of a human right to a healthy environment, states could make use of the United Nations human rights system to regularly monitor whether adequate actions as well as appropriate cooperation programs with respect to adaptation, mitigation and loss and damage are in place. The Universal Periodic Review Mechanism, the Special Procedures (consisting of thematic and country-specific mandates) and the treaty body (a new one would be created with a new binding human rights treaty) would help states to engage into a dialogue, make concrete recommendations, and strengthen capacities and technical assistance, in order to protect human rights in the face of climate impacts and in order for climate policies to be implemented in consistence with human rights standards. A human right to a healthy environment is oriented towards protecting individuals and communities from adverse climate change impacts today and in the future. By emphasizing the duty to international cooperation, it shows strong parallels with the debate on ETOs and hence, bears the potential to advance inter-national justice (by providing assistance) and intra-societal justice (by fulfilling the rights of societal groups). An environmental human right would also take the interests of future generations into account by fostering cooperative activities to guarantee clean air, water and land. This means this emerging norm has the potential to contribute to inter-generational justice – reflecting the demand for protecting future generations on the basis of equity and common but differentiated responsibilities stipulated in the 1992 UNFCCC. Thus, a human right to a healthy environment can be considered the most encompassing step that would contribute to achieving more inter- national, intra-societal and inter-generational justice. 16 5. Advantages and Disadvantages of a Human Rights-Based Approach to Climate Justice What are the advantages and disadvantages of a human rights-based approach to climate justice – and of strengthening the human rights regime, i.e. ETOs, procedural rights and a human right to a healthy environment, in the context of contemporary climate challenges? Let us begin with carving out the advantages. First, human rights can bridge the divide between normative justice claims and empirical climate practices, i.e. human activities to diminish climate injustice. Human rights constitute a normative concept, but at the same time, rights instruments also entail concrete empirical implementation measures. Since the adoption of the UDHR, recognition for equal and inalienable rights has been understood as building the foundation for justice. 67 Today, scholars increasingly link already existing human rights obligations to climate change 68 and climate justice. 69 Knox reminded negotiating state parties in Paris that: “States’ human rights obligations also encompass climate change,” and that “[…] they must ensure that all of their actions comply with their human rights obligations. That includes their actions relating to climate change”. 70 In fact, there is no single state government in the world anymore that has not committed to at least one of the UN core conventions on human rights. 71 And these entail concrete implementation measures, including ETOs in conventions containing economic, social and cultural rights, which can serve as a guidepost for just climate practices. This means realizing existing human rights, closing implementation gaps and further developing the human rights system can be understood as a concrete climate practice diminishing inter-national, intra-societal and inter-generational injustice. Second, the language of human rights is strong; it emphasizes the need for immediate political action and cannot be easily ignored in contemporary politics. 72 State actors from liberal and democratic countries usually shy away from neglecting human rights because they consider them to be an integral part of their identity. 73 Human rights models, such as the Boomerang Pattern or the Spiral Model of Human Rights Change, emphasize how human rights norms become adopted and internalized if pressure from above, i.e. by transnational human rights networks, and from below, i.e. by domestic opposition groups, is exerted. 74 Thus, embedded in a human rights discourse, climate change is framed a matter of immediate human urgency – as opposed to a technocratic matter of interstate negotiations. It emphasizes a “pressingly relevant” need for action employing the “muscular language of human rights” 75 and it can unleash argumentative, persuasive or pressure mechanisms exerted on state actors to change 17 climate policies and make them more human-centered. The employment of pressure and persuasion mechanisms becomes more likely as recently also some of the big human rights NGOs, Human Rights Watch and Amnesty International, have taken up the issue of climate change and become particularly active in this regard. 76 Third, by employing a human rights-based approach to climate justice, the situation of individual and collective rights-holders becomes central (as opposed to tedious state negotiations). Human rights define the relationship between a state government and its citizens. 77 Rights norms have a hybrid function; they constitute inter-state regulations, but also define norms relevant within societies, for respective rights-holders. This focus on the rights-holders is particularly important if one takes the trans-boundary character of climate change and its unequal implications on vulnerable groups and individuals into consideration. Women, children, elderly, disabled or indigenous peoples and standards for their protection move to the center of attention and policy solutions – as opposed to political negotiations. Fourth, a human rights perspective can be fruitful for assigning obligations. In many cases, these can be derived from the required implementation measures of already existing human rights treaties state parties have committed to. Obligations do not only exist between a ratifying state government and its citizens but also between a ratifying capable state government and the citizens of other, less capable countries. This duty to international cooperation can be found in the UN Charter, the UDHR and the ICESCR. 78 Obligations to international cooperation are also stipulated in targeted treaties, like the CRC, and other conventions containing economic, social and cultural rights. The 2011 Maastricht Principles constitute a recent attempt to strengthen extraterritorial obligations of states and IOs as well as state responsibility for the acts and omissions of non-state actors and transnational corporations. 79 Fifth, human rights and the obligation to international cooperation as reaffirmed in the Maastricht Principles can build the constitutive basis for climate policy programs. Procedural safeguards can guide the design of climate policies, like REDD+ programs, CDM or SDM projects as well as green economy policies. This means a “human rights-based approach to climate change negotiations, policies and measures” 80 can help vulnerable states in cooperating with capable states and IOs to face the consequences of climate change, to design just climate policies and to implement the human rights of their citizens at the same time. Finally, a human rights framework can build an analytical umbrella around many relevant issues pertaining to climate change. It accommodates various aspects of human security, of 18 migration and the protection of climate refugees, and – by fostering economic, social and cultural rights – it frequently enters common ground with development issues. Hence, a broad-ranging human rights framework embraces a variety of issues relating to climate justice (that cannot be merely treated in isolation from each other) with a view to protecting affected vulnerable groups and individuals. The main disadvantages or challenges pertaining to a human rights-based approach to climate justice are, first of all, enforcement and compliance. Although some human rights conventions, such as the CRC or CEDAW, have been nearly universally ratified, key gaps in implementation prevail. In IR scholarship on norms, this “compliance gap” 81 has been grasped in conceptual differentiations between “prescriptive status” and “norm-consistent behavior”. 82 Progressive human rights realization of economic, social and cultural rights is a key challenge and the consequences of climate change exacerbate implementation challenges. The chronic under-fulfillment of human rights goals often lead to skepticism with respect to adopting a rights approach to climate justice. 83 Second, scholars and practitioners have pointed to the impossibility of disentangling cause and effect when it comes to climate change implications on human rights. 84 Anthropogenic climate change has mainly been caused in industrialized states, mostly by private companies, and has devastating effect among vulnerable societal groups in developing countries that often lack the resources to adapt. According to human rights treaties, the ratifying state governments are primarily responsible for respecting, protecting and promoting the rights of their citizens. This would mean that – in the first place – governments of developing states (who do not bear the main responsibility for climate change) have the obligation to secure their citizens’ human rights. If they are lacking the capability to do so, the international community has the duty to cooperate. This complex constellation of cause and effect over time, however, as well as the involvement of public and private actors at various levels and in different world regions makes identifying duty-bearers and assigning (extraterritorial) obligations an ambiguous task 85 . Third, there are concerns about potentially over-expanding the international human rights catalogue, which comes with the risk of devaluing it. 86 Since 2008, there have been six resolutions passed by the Human Rights Council on the relationship between climate change and human rights. The question is whether, next to non-binding resolutions and declarations, a new convention on the same level as the core UN human rights treaties can evolve (potentially embracing an international human right to a healthy environment). There could be 19 strong arguments for rights concerns in the context of climate change to be covered under the ICESCR – and even adding another optional protocol to it can been regarded as a fairly ambitious endeavor. 87 The skepticism around economic, social and cultural rights and even more so regarding collective rights will make the adoption and implementation of environmental human rights a difficult task. Fourth, inter-generational aspects are difficult to work in practice by current decision-makers and have so far mostly been addressed by scholars in Political Theory and Philosophy. 88 Although scholars argue that constitutionally guaranteeing a fundamental human right to a healthy environment today, would enable favorable conditions for rights protection in the future 89 , several concerns remain. Who exactly can speak for future generations, how can they be represented and in which way can we assess their interests? 90 Protecting the rights of future generations in a changing environment means to reshape current political systems and institutions 91 , which is quite an ambitious endeavor and often too far away from current political realities and agendas. Fifth, there are ideological tensions between the human rights and the environmentalist movement. Whereas the human rights movement has an anthropocentric orientation, placing human beings in the center of decision-making, environmentalists rather follow an ecocentric approach, focusing on the entire ecosystem. This tension can lead to different priorities when it comes to the formulation of policy programs, specifically on issues like development, economic growth or population control, 92 and can lead to a situation in which a human rights framework may lack the necessary support of environmental groups. Finally, the human right to a healthy environment as a collective right is severely contested. Collective rights belong to the third dimension and are not bindingly anchored in the UN human rights edifice due to many states questioning their universality. Thus, environmental rights have found entrance in many national constitutions and some regional conventions but there is resistance regarding the establishment of an international human right. Although there is an intensive academic discourse encompassing normative claims for a right to ecological space 93 , environmental rights 94 or concrete formulations for a substantive human right for the protection of the environment 95 , its development in practice still is controversial. An awareness of these arguments and counterarguments is important for taking a clear position in this debate. In this article, I argue in favor of strengthening procedural rights, extraterritorial state obligations and a human right to a healthy environment as relevant ways to diminish climate injustice. Let me briefly explain how I would reply to the disadvantages 20 or counterarguments brought forward above. Enforcement and compliance deficits within the human rights system only partly relate to lacking political will and are very often caused by missing capacities, resources and expertise 96 . Thus, increased cooperation leads to better compliance, especially when it comes to economic, social and cultural rights that are mostly affected by climate change and climate politics. If the international community cooperates, we do not need to disentangle cause and effect in more detail than this was done within the UNFCCC (Annex I and non-Annex I countries) already. Moellendorf, for example, argues for an “ability to pay” account in climate change treaties signaling that this duty needs to be taken seriously and that countries have the right to sustainable development. 97 This is exactly how the duty to cooperate in human rights treaties can be understood; those countries that have ratified and have the capacities to implement rights financially and technically support those countries that have ratified but lack capacities to implement. There are many examples illustrating how ideological tensions between the human rights and environmentalist movement do not prevent NGOs or IOs to collaborate and take a hybrid approach rather than insisting on ecocentric or anthropocentric arguments. An interesting case is the inter-constituency alliance at COP 21 in Paris mentioned in the introduction of this article, in which environmental, human rights, youth, gender and indigenous peoples’ groups worked together. Since Bonn 2017, the inter-constituency alliance has been renamed into ‘coalition for rights’ taking even more actors on board and it increasingly makes references to ecosystem integrity as a key principle, together with indigenous peoples rights, food security, public participation, gender equality and just transition, in implementing the Paris agreement. 98 Moreover, human rights have always been further developed in response to current challenges in the world. Thus, they are dynamic and not static. And even though we should not over- expand the human rights catalogue, we should also not hamper developments in response to serious threats. Probably the most significant example for this is the development of international human rights after World War II. Individual rights above the state and independent of nationality at that time were understood to be the foundation for freedom, peace and justice in the world. Facing the severe challenges of climate change today, we will most probably see the human rights evolving from individual civil and political rights to collective intergenerational environmental rights. 21 6. Conclusions In this article, I have tried to link considerations on climate justice with current human rights developments relating to climate change and climate policies. My aim was to show in which way rights developments and pertinent debates can be linked to the normative claims brought forward in considerations on climate justice. This analysis helps to develop a better understanding of the linkage between climate justice and human rights but also how concrete climate justice practices can be shaped through further human rights development and effective enforcement. I have argued that further developing a human right to a healthy environment would be the most encompassing step to address climate injustice. The analysis reveals the following results: Procedural and substantive human rights obligations relating to climate change and climate policies are still evolving. Procedural rights have, for instance, been adopted as institutional safeguards for REDD+ programs in 2010 but their effectiveness in program implementation have not been comprehensively evaluated yet. Further developments in this respect, including safeguards for the CDM or the newly established SDM as well as for green economy policies can be expected. They have the potential to protect particularly vulnerable groups from the adverse effects of climate policies and hence, can advance intra-societal justice. As procedural rights have entered UNFCCC negotiations, prospects of their advancement are particularly high and we can expect further institutional developments in this respect in the short run. ETOs have their origins in the UN Charter in 1945 and gained significant meaning with the adoption of the ICESCR in 1966. By strengthening the duty to international cooperation in the area of economic, social and cultural rights, ETOs bear the potential to foster inter-national justice. By assisting states to fulfill these rights for respective individuals and communities, they also further intra-societal justice. In the face of climatic challenges, ETOs will be advanced through the commentaries of the human rights treaty monitoring bodies, first and foremost the Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, but also through regional court decisions and case law. This is already relevant today and will receive further attention and changes in human rights soft law in the coming years. An international human right to a healthy environment would be the most encompassing advancement in the global human rights edifice. It would not only promote inter-national and intra-societal but also inter-generational justice by entailing duties to preserve the environment, i.e. water, air and soil, for future generations. 99 There are many sceptics pertinent to the emergence of such a collective human right to a healthy environment and I 22 have discussed a number of counter-arguments above. In November 2017, John Knox has held consultations on draft guidelines on human rights and the environment including procedural and substantive state obligations. These guidelines can be understood as a further important step towards establishing an international human right to a healthy environment. Institutionalization processes of environmental human rights are further progressing and need to be supported to diminish climate injustice. It is important to note that in the face of a changing climate and demands for more climate justice, human rights are changing and developing – from individual civil and political rights to collective intergenerational rights. The systematization of the climate justice literature presented above can also be used as an analytical framework for IR scholars interested in regime complexity 100 , institutional interaction and institutional interplay 101 of climate change with other policy fields, such as human rights, but also development, economics and trade. In this way, climate justice scholarship can be usefully integrated into empirical studies in IR to evaluate institutional and policy developments against normative claims formulated by Political Theorists and Philosophers on how to diminish climate injustices. It has the potential to bring often disconnected debates together and to shape ideas on concrete climate justice practices in a number of policy fields. 23 Endnotes 1 Steven Humphreys, ‘Climate Justice: The Claim of the Past’, Journal of Human Rights and the Environment 5(0), 2014, pp. 134–148. 2 Ludvig Beckman and Edward Page, ‘Perspectives on justice, democracy and global climate change’, Environmental Politics 17(4), 2008, pp. 527-535. 3 Edward Page, Climate Change, Justice and Future Generations, (Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, 2006), p. 50. 4 Humphreys, ‘Climate Justice’, pp. 141-147. 5 Steve Vanderheiden, ‘Justice in the Greenhouse: Climate Change and the Idea of Fairness’, Social Philosophy Today 19, 2004, pp. 89–101. 6 ‘A New Climate Agreement Must Include Human Rights Protections For All’, OHCHR 2014, available at: http://www.ohchr.org/Documents/HRBodies/SP/SP_To_UNFCCC.pdf (accessed 28 February 2017). 7 ‘Promoting the Geneva Pledge for Climate Action’, Human Rights and Climate Change Working Group 2015, available at: http://climaterights.org/our-work/unfccc/geneva-pledge/ (accessed 28 February 2017). 8 ‘Draft Declaration on Human Rights and Climate Change’, available at: http://gnhre.org/wp- content/uploads/2015/11/GNHRE-draft-declaration1.pdf (accessed 28 February 2017). 9 ‘Paris Agreement: Adopted at the 21 st Conference of the Parties’, UNFCCC 2015, available at: http://unfccc.int/files/essential_background/convention/application/pdf/english_paris_agreement.pdf (accessed 10 January 2017). 10 The initial ambition of the inter-constituency alliance was to anchor human rights in article two of the operative part which defines the purpose of the Paris agreement. Although this could not be realized, the inter-constituency alliance still considers itself to have substantially contributed to including human rights in the final agreement, although only in the preambulatory clauses. 11 Hans-Peter Schmitz and Kathryn Sikkink, ‘International Human Rights’, in Walter Carlsnaes, Thomas Risse, and Beth A. Simmons (eds) Handbook of International Relations (London: SAGE, 2013), p. 827. 12 Practices are competent performances structuring world politics, giving meaning to international action and interaction by reproducing, changing and reinforcing action and interaction. Thus, climate justice practices can be understood as policy-specific every day activities to diminish climate injustice. Emmanuel Adler and Vincent Pouliot, ‘International Practices’, International Theory 3(1), 2011, pp. 1-36. 13 OHCHR, Report of the Office of the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights on the Relationship between Climate Change and Human Rights, Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights, 2009), p.13. 14 Silvia Maus, ‘Hand in Hand against Climate Change: Cultural Human Rights and the Protection of Cultural Heritage’, Cambridge Review of International Affairs 27(4), 2014, pp. 699–716. 15 OHCHR, Report, pp.14–15. 16 James R. May and Erin Daly, Global Environmental Constitutionalism, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2014). 17 Based on data from: Marcos A. Orellana and Alyssa Johl, Climate Change and Human Rights: A Primer, (Washington: The Center for International Environmental Law, 2013) and supplemented with data from: OHCHR, Report. 18 Jeanette Schade and Wolfgang Obergassel, ‘Human Rights and the Clean Development Mechanism’, Cambridge Review of International Affairs 27(4), 2014, pp. 717–735. 19 Human Rights Watch, There is No Time Left: Climate Change, Environmental Threats, and Human Rights in Turkana County, Kenya, (New York, Human Rights Watch, 2015). 24 20 Eve Bratman, ‘Passive Revolution in the Green Economy: Activism and the Belo Monte Dam’, International Environmental Agreements 15(1), 2015, pp. 61–77. 21 Human Rights Watch, What Will Happen if Hunger Comes? Abuses Against the Indigenous Peoples of Ethiopia’s Lower Omo Valley, (New York: Human Rights Watch, 2012). 22 Beckman and Page, ‘Perspectives on justice’. 23 Humphreys, ‘Climate Justice’. 24 Karen Morrow, ‘Climate Change and Human Rights: The Defining Dilemma of Our Times?’, Journal of Human Rights and the Environment 1(2), 2010, p. 132. 25 Or climate justice in relation to the non-human world. See: Clare Palmer, ‘Does Nature Matter? The Place of the Nonhuman in the Ethics of Climate Change’ in Denis G. Arnold (ed) The Ethics of Global Climate Change (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011), pp. 272-291. 26 Henry Shue, Climate Justice: Vulnerability and Protection, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014). 27 Moellendorf, Darrel, The Moral Challenge of Dangerous Climate Change: Values, Poverty and Policy, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2014). 28 Humphreys, ‘Climate Justice’, pp. 141-147. 29 Richard P. Hiskes, The Human Right to a Green Future: Environmental Rights and Intergenerational Justice, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009). 30 Paul G. Harris, Alice S.Y. Chow and Rasmus Karlsson, ‘China and Climate Justice: Moving beyond Statism’, International Environmental Agreements 13(3), 2013, pp. 293–301. 31 Peter Newell, ‘Race, Class and the Global Politics of Environmental Inequality’, Global Environmental Politics 5(3), 2005, p. 70 and p. 87. 32 OHCHR, Report, pp. 15–18. 33 These rights are anchored in the 1966 ICCPR and in the 1998 Aarhus Convention. 34 ‘The Cancun Agreements’, available at: http://unfccc.int/resource/docs/2010/cop16/eng/07a01.pdf#page=2 (accessed 10 January 2017). 35 Richard P. Hiskes, ‘The Right to a Green Future: Human Rights, Environmentalism and Intergenerational Justice’ Human Rights Quarterly 27(4), 2005, pp. 1346–1364. 36 Hiskes, ‘The Right to a Green Future’. 37 Simon Caney, ‘Climate Change, Energy Rights and Equality’ in Denis G. Arnold (ed) The Ethics of Global Climate Change (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011), pp. 77–103. 38 Shue, Climate Justice. 39 Beckman and Page, ‘Perspectives on justice’. 40 Sigrun Skogly, Beyond National Borders: States’ Human Rights Obligations in International Cooperation (Antwerpen: Intersentia, 2006), p.5. 41 Caroline Mair, The Maastricht Principles and Environmental Law (London: Foundation for International Environmental Law and Development, 2012), p. 3. 42 de Schutter, Olivier et al., ‘Commentary to the Maastricht Principles on Extraterritorial Obligations of States in the Area of Economic, Social and Cultural Rights’ Human Rights Quarterly 34(4), 2012, pp. 1091–1104. 43 International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, available at: http://www.ohchr.org/EN/ProfessionalInterest/Pages/CESCR.aspx (accessed 10 January 2017), Art. 2. 44 John Knox, Report of the Independent Expert on the Issue of Human Rights Obligations Relating to the Enjoyment of a Safe, Clean, Healthy and Sustainable Environment (Geneva: Human Rights Council, 2014), p. 18. 45 ‘The Climate Change and Human Rights Petition’ available at: http://www.greenpeace.org/seasia/ph/press/releases/Worlds-largest-carbon-producers-ordered-to-respond-to- 25 allegations-of-human-rights--abuses-from-climate-change/The-Climate-Change-and-Human-Rights-Petition/ (accessed 28 February 2017). 46 Marc Limon, ‘Human Rights and Climate Change: Constructing a Case for Political Action’ Harvard Environmental Law Review 33(2), 2009, pp. 439–476. 47 John Knox, ‘Climate Change and Human Rights Law’ Virginia Journal of International Law 50(1), 2009, p. 208. 48 ‘Maastricht Principles on Extraterritorial Obligations of States in the Area of Economic, Social and Cultural Rights’ available at: http://www.ciel.org/wp-content/uploads/2015/05/Maastricht_ETO_Principles_21Oct11.pdf (accessed 10 January 2017). 49 Aarti Gupta, ‘Transparency Under Scrutiny: Information Disclosure in Global Environmental Governance’ Global Environmental Politics 8(2), 2008, pp. 1–7. 50 Gupta, ‘Transparency Under Scrutiny’, p. 3–4. 51 Alan Boyle, ‘Human Rights and the Environment: Where Next?’ European Journal of International Law 23(3), 2012, pp. 622–626. 52 Schade and Obergassel‚‘Human Rights and the Clean Development Mechanism’. 53 ‘Press Statement – In landmark decision, Panama withdraws UN registration for Barro Blanco hydrodam project’, Carbon Market Watch 2016, available at: http://carbonmarketwatch.org/press-statement-in-landmark- decision-panama-withdraws-un-registration-for-barro-blanco-hydrodam-project/ (accessed 28 February). 54 ‘COP 22’, Carbon Market Watch 2016, available at: http://carbonmarketwatch.org/category/climate- negotiations/cop22/ (accessed 28 February 2017). 55 OHCHR, Comments and recommendations of OHCHR regarding the future UNFCC Sustainable Development Mechanism, (Geneva: OHCHR, 2016). 56 Knox, Report of the Independent Expert, p. 9. 57 Roe, Stephanie et al., Safeguards in REDD+ and Forest Carbon Standards: A Review of Social, Environmental and Procedural Standards and Application (Amsterdam, ClimateFocus, 2013). 58 Stephen J. Turner, A Global Environmental Right (Abingdon: Routledge, 2014). 59 OHCHR, Report, p 3. 60 James W. Nickel, ‘The Human Right to a Safe Environment: Philosophical Perspectives on Its Scope and Justification’, Yale Journal of International Law 18 (1), 1993, pp. 281-295; Tim Hayward, Constitutional Environmental Rights, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005). 61 Knox, ‘Climate Change and Human Rights Law’, pp. 177–178. 62 Stephen Humphreys, ‘Climate Change and International Human Rights Law’ in Rosemary Rayfuse and Shirley V. Scott (eds), International Law in the Era of Climate Change (Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, 2012), pp. 29–57. 63 David R. Boyd, The Environmental Rights Revolution: A Global Study of Constitutions, Human Rights, and the Environment (Vancouver: University of British Columbia Press, 2012). 64 Knox, Report of the Independent Expert, p. 8. 65 Knox, ‘Climate Change and Human Rights Law’, p. 212. 66 John Knox, Draft Guidelines on Human Rights and the Environment (Geneva: Human Rights Council, 2017). 67 ‘Universal Declaration of Human Rights’ available at: http://www.un.org/en/universal-declaration-human- rights/ (accessed 11 January 2017), preamble. 68 ‘COP21: ’States’ human rights obligations encompass climate change’ – UN expert’ available at: http://www.ohchr.org/EN/NewsEvents/Pages/DisplayNews.aspx?NewsID=16836&LangID=E (accessed 21 July 2016). 69 Humphreys, ‘Climate Justice’. 70 ‘COP21: ’States’ human rights obligations encompass climate change’ – UN expert’. 71 COP21: ’States’ human rights obligations encompass climate change’ – UN expert’. 26 72 Hiskes, The Human Right to a Green Future, p. 2. 73 Thomas Risse, Stephen C. Ropp, and Kathryn Sikkink, The Power of Human Rights: International Norms and Domestic Change (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999), p. 23. 74 Thomas Risse, Stephen C. Ropp, and Kathryn Sikkink (eds), The Persistent Power of Human Rights: From Commitment to Compliance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013. 75 Hiskes, The Human Right to a Green Future, pp. 3–5. 76 ‘Joint Statement: Protection of Human Rights from Climate Change Requires Urgent Shift to 100% Renewable Energy for All’, available at: https://www.amnesty.org/en/documents/pol30/3033/2015/en (accessed 17 June 2016). 77 Schmitz and Sikkink, ‘International Human Rights’, p. 827. 78 de Schutter, Olivier et al., ‘Commentary to the Maastricht Principles’, pp. 1091–1104. 79 ‘Maastricht Principles on Extraterritorial Obligations of States’. 80 OHCHR, Applying a Human Rights-Based Approach to Climate Change Negotiations, Policies and Measures (Geneva: OHCHR, 2010). 81 Xinyuan Dai, ‘The “Compliance Gap” and the Efficacy of International Human Rights Institutions’ in Thomas Risse, Stephen Ropp, and Kathryn Sikkink (eds), The Persistent Power of Human Rights: From Commitment to Compliance (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013), p. 85. 82 Risse, Ropp, and Sikkink, The Power of Human Rights, p. 29, p. 33. 83 Kerri Woods, Human Rights and Environmental Sustainability (Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Press, 2010). 84 Dudai, ‘Climate Change and Human Rights Practice’ Journal of Human Rights Practice 1(2), 2009, pp. 294– 307. 85 On indirect or mediated responsibilities see also: Robin Attfield, ‘Mediated Responsibilities, Global Warming and the Scope of Ethics’ Journal of Social Philosophy 40(2), 2009, pp. 225-236. 86 Philip Alston, ‘Conjuring up New Human Rights: a Proposal for Quality Control’ American Journal of International Law 78(3), 1984, pp. 607–621. 87 Dudai, ‘Climate Change and Human Rights Practice’, p. 305. 88 Hiskes, The Human Right to a Green Future. 89 Tim Hayward, ‘Human Rights Versus Emissions Rights: Climate Justice and the Equitable Distribution of Ecological Space’ Ethics and International Affairs 21(4), 2007, pp. 431–450. 90 Dudai, ‘Climate Change and Human Rights Practice’, p. 302. 91 Beckman and Page, ‘Perspectives on justice’, p. 529; for a different perspective see also Kerri Woods, ‘The rights of (future) humans qua humans’ Journal of Human Rights 15(2), 2016, pp.291-306. 92 Dudai, ‘Climate Change and Human Rights Practice’. 93 Hayward, ‘Human Rights Versus Emissions Rights’. 94 Hiskes, The Human Right to a Green Future. 95 Turner, A Global Environmental Right. 96 Risse, Ropp, and Sikkink, The Power of Human Rights. 97 Moellendorf, The Moral Challenge of Climate Change, p.7. 98 CIEL et al., ‘Delivering on the Paris Promises: Combating Climate Change While Protecting Rights’ available at: https://www.deliveringonparis.com/wp-content/uploads/2017/06/Delivering-On-Paris-Web.pdf (accessed 26 November 2017). 99 Hiskes, The Human Right to a Green Future, p. 143. 100 Kenneth W. Abbott, ‘Strengthening the Transnational Regime Complex for Climate Change’ Transnational Environmental Law 3(1), 2014, pp. 57–88; Eero Palmujoki, ‘Fragmentation and Diversification of Climate Change Governance in International Society’ International Relations 27(2), 2013, pp. 180–201. 27 101 Thomas Gehring and Sebastian Oberthür, ‘The Causal Mechanisms of Interaction between International Institutions’ European Journal of International Relations 15(1), 2009, pp. 125–156. work_gygdznd5tjgu3mgpsvbqmnvhge ---- The 'third way' and social justice Journal of Political Ideologies (2001), 6(2), 231–235 COMMUNICATION The ‘third way’ and social justice MARCEL WISSENBURG Faculty of Policy Sciences, University of Nijmegen, PO Box 9108, 6500 HK Nijmegen, The Netherlands ABSTRACT In reaction to Steve Buckler’s and David Dolowitz’s earlier contri- bution to this journal, I argue that New Labour’s ‘third way’ cannot be founded on John Rawls’s theory of justice. ‘Third way’ practice contradict s Rawls’s ideas about both redistributiv e justice and social justice in a broader sense. Rawlsian output justice Social democracy was the � rst to emerge out of the ideological ruins of 1989 with a new perspective on a changing world: the ‘third way’. Recently, Steve Buckler and David Dolowitz1 argued that more can be said in defence of New Labour’s ‘third way’ than has been said so far. With this ‘so far’, one can refer both to writings of the British and other ‘third way’ parties’ politicians ,2 and to those of ‘third way’s academic defenders like Miliband and Giddens.3 What all these texts have in common is, after all, that they mix two elements where three would be needed. ‘Third way’ advocates offer analyses of empirical data and normative claims. What is missing is a theoretical foundation justifyin g the passage from is to ought. The thesis Buckler and Dolowitz defend is that John Rawls’s theory of justice may offer such an underpinning , that in fact ‘third way’ principles and policy already re� ect Rawls’s ideas. I shall argue instead that the ‘third way’ as we know it � ts neither the more familiar part of Rawls’s work, the theory of the just distributio n of the bene� ts and burdens of social co-operation (‘output justice’), nor criteria of social justice in a broader sense. In the end, Buckler, Dolowitz and I might very well agree that the ‘third way’ is an approximation of Rawls’s theory. Yet for now I believe that the principles of the ‘third way’ need serious revision before there can be any talk of an equilibrium between the philosoph y of social justice and the practices of the ‘third way’. One reason for Buckler and Dolowitz to believe in a convergence between Rawls and the ‘third way’ is that the latter would re� ect Rawls’s conviction that there is an irresolvable disagreement on the de� nition of the good.4 This brought Rawls to the conclusion that a theory of social justice needs to be founded on ISSN 1356-931 7 print; 1469-9613 online/01/020231–05 Ó 2001 Taylor & Francis Ltd DOI: 10.1080 /1356931012005387 6 MARCEL WISSENBURG an impartial conception of the right. It is true that we � nd, for instance, Blair and Schröder saying similar things—that governments cannot and should not pre- scribe what kinds of lives people should lead and what kinds of things they should value. Yet the practice of the ‘third way’ deviates considerably from the promise, as I hope to show when I reach my fourth point. A second indication of convergence would lie in the Rawlsian Difference Principle, which Buckler and Dolowitz reformulate as ‘the arranging of social and economic inequalitie s such that they are to the bene� t of all under condition s of fair equality of opportunity ’. The test for whether inequality bene� ts all is that the social system ‘must enhance the long-term interests of the least well off groups in society’.5 This description certainly � ts Blair’s and Schröder’s belief that perfect equality is not a desirable objective for the ‘third way’; we should accept that some inequality is justi� ed.6 But the description does not � t Rawls: Rawls’s true position on inequality is one of ‘equality unless’, not ‘inequality so that’: ‘… there are conceptions of justice that are recognizably egalitarian, even though certain signi� cant disparities are permitted. The two principle s of justice fall, I assume, under this heading’.7 Buckler and Dolowitz go so far as to claim that Rawls accepts inequality because it contributes ‘to ef� cient wealth creation in a system where the prospects of all are potentiall y enhanced’,8 which may be or may not be empirically true for a ‘third way’ society. However, for Rawls ef� ciency and justice are distinct desiderata :9 a slave society where freedom is ‘potentially ’ attainable can be perfectly ef� cient but will never be just. In addition, Rawls rejects the notion of desert or merit as a basis for the unequal distributio n of (say) income: it betrays an inadmissible partiality to a particular theory of the good.10 Thirdly, Buckler and Dolowitz claim that Rawls is concerned about proce- dures not outcomes: unlike many theories of social justice, his does not call for an equal distributio n of the bene� ts and burdens of social co-operation, or for a distributio n mechanism that satis� es some other criterion for a just state of affairs, an outcome. What matters for Rawls is that his two principles are followed, ‘whatever [the] outcome happens to be’.11 The result may be equality one day, inequality the next. Again, this re� ects Schröder’s and Blair’s idea that equality of outcome is not intrinsicall y valuable but disregards people’s efforts. And again, it does not re� ect Rawls. Apart from rejecting desert, Rawls does care about outcomes: the point about the Difference Principle is that it should be applied so as to bring the worst off as close to equality as possible. For Rawls, there can be no justi� cation for social inequality in itself: inequality is the result of systems and institution s that differently reward people on the basis of their natural or social differences, differences which are (in accordance with the is-does-not-imply-ough t rule) morally indifferent. Rawls’s commitment to out- comes also becomes clear in his brief discussio n of Amartya Sen’s suggestio n to replace primary social goods as a distributio n criterion by ‘basic capabilities ’, i.e., by what individual s in their particular situations can actually do with their primary social goods. Rawls rejects Sen’s suggestion , not because outcomes do not matter but because Sen’s criterion is impractical.12 232 THE ‘THIRD WAY’ AND SOCIAL JUSTICE Fourthly, Rawls and the ‘third way’ would converge in applying the Differ- ence Principle to opportunities.13 Yet even if ‘opportunities ’ and ‘primary social goods’ were interchangeable (which they are not), Rawls’s opportunitie s are not those of Blair and Schröder. In ‘third way’ practice, opportunitie s are opportuni - ties for self-suf� ciency given a free market society, which comes down to creating incentives for � nding work and for becoming � exible workers able even to take jobs they would not dream of desiring—and to creating disincentive s for those who will not co-operate. Think of the British New Deal programmes established to ‘cater to the needs of [disadvantaged] groups by offering them packages of support and advice designed to ensure that they are aware of and can take advantage of employment opportunitie s where appropriate’.14 All this deviates from Rawls’s theory in two respects: it lacks impartiality with regard to the individuals ’ theories of the good (forcing them to subject to the dictates of the labour market), and it takes the present free market society for granted, whereas Rawls sees it as one possible context for social justice among many. Finally, Buckler and Dolowitz point out that in providing opportunities , the ‘third way’ wishes to pay special attention to ‘groups that are […] marginalized due to arbitrary factors’.15 This could be interpreted as a re� ection of Rawls’s principle of Fair Equality of Opportunity , but looks are deceiving. As we have just seen, the ‘third way’ de� nes equal opportunit y not as equal opportunit y to attain a particular position or not try at all (thus respecting the individual ’s theory of the good and plan of life), but as an equal opportunity to attain any position the labour market cares to offer and no other. Social justice Social justice is more than distributiv e output justice: it also relates to the input side, i.e., the distributio n of access to the creation of the bene� ts and burdens of social co-operation (hence fair equality of opportunity) , and to commutative justice, i.e., justice among individuals .16 Although Buckler and Dolowitz do not discuss them, it is worthwhile noting that ‘third way’ theory and practice cannot meet standards for these aspects of social justice either. First of all, the ‘third way’ disregards justice in the input sphere. One of the most distinguishin g features of socialism and social democracy used to be that they questioned the existing system or mode of production ; the ‘third way’, however, lets supply rule. It is as if the ‘third way’ has thrown away the baby with the bath water: in relinquishin g its resistance to market mechanisms, it has also abandoned its objections to capitalisti c ownership relations and to the expression of uncritical, potentiall y harmful preferences that market mechanisms thrive on. On the one hand, employers continue to rule the labour market and dictate which jobs are offered, which qualities are desired, and by implication which human beings are useful; on the other, producers dictate which products are offered and are considered desirable or valuable. The ‘third way’s’ interpret- ation of ‘opportunities ’ in the � eld of labour relations at the very least fails to encourage, but probably directly discourages, the development and expression of 233 MARCEL WISSENBURG plans of life and theories of the good that deviate from the ideal of the useful drone. In this respect, the ‘third way’ silences social, political and moral critique before it can even be expressed. A second problem is that the ‘third way’, in the sphere of output social justice and particularly in the � eld of labour, fails to guarantee distributiv e justice as such. Justice is a remedial virtue, a virtue for an imperfect world of scarcity and egoism.17 With its interpretatio n of social justice as attainable by commutative means, the ‘third way’ offers this remedial virtue to the ideal participant in market procedures: self-suf� cient, self-conscious , responsible individuals . Jus- tice is meted out in the market place, and (ideally) given to those who qualify for the criteria of the market place: those who work harder or perform better receive more than those who do not. Obviously, without further remedial measures this would lead to the exclusion of those who do not qualify: the lazy, politicall y motivated defectors, and people who cannot qualify as easily. The last category consists of all those parties for whom the redistributiv e welfare state was invented in the � rst place. In other words, it is still up to old welfare state institution s to deal with these sources of injustice, not the new institution s introduced (and given political priority) by the ‘third way’. Thirdly, the ‘third way’ embraces the market without warranting commutative justice. Ideally, following Aristotle, the market is a place where free and (therefore) equally powerful individuals meet and voluntarily exchange goods (or anything else). In real life in modern society, supply and demand are seldom equally powerful, and therefore seldom in equal negotiatin g positions . In purely formal terms, a market is just when both parties receive what in their individua l eyes is the equivalent of what they gave. Given unequal starting positions , the more powerful party is by de� nition capable of dictating what is on offer on the market, and of raising the price of its product. A � nal reason to question the possibilit y of reconciling the ‘third way’ with social justice is that by refusing to create a completely free market, ‘third way’ politics contradicts its own commitment to moral pluralism and to a reduction of state interference in civil society. This objection relates in particular to the privatisatio n of public services practised in ‘third way’ countries: it is usually the institution providing the service that is privatised, not the product itself. Citizens are still legally obliged to insure themselves against illness, unemployment, old age, and so on—nowadays, they just have to get it elsewhere than at a government agency, and they can (usually) choose between (hopefully) compet- ing social security providers or job mediators. Citizens may not be legally obliged to use electricity, water and gas, garbage disposal, telephone, television, radio and public transport, yet in practice most of these early twentieth-centur y luxuries have become unavoidable basic needs for virtually every twenty-� rst century European. As long as there is demand for a product, supplyin g it can be pro� table; as long as there is no alternative to the product, the market for it is safe. Obviously, obliging citizens to consume services, or not enabling them to consume alternatives, matches with the ‘third way’ intention of keeping the 234 THE ‘THIRD WAY’ AND SOCIAL JUSTICE welfare state alive at lower costs (in public spending, though not necessarily from the point of view of the individua l citizen’s wallet). But it does not match with the idea of a free market, nor with the intention of offering ‘opportunities ’ (in the broad sense), of moving away from a paternalisti c prescription of the terms of a good life towards an impartial respect for the existence of a plurality of life-styles and theories of the good. Thus, there appear to be limits to the degree to which the ‘third way’ is willing to grant responsibilit y to individuals . What is more, the ‘third way’s’ privatisatio n strategy does not result in a reduction of government interference in civil society. By obliging citizens to consume certain services, they also take on a duty to see to it that these services are provided at affordable prices. Hence, they still have to control and regulate the market for public services. The ‘third way’ unlocked a potential source of support for the welfare state never thought of before, at a moment when it was needed more than ever before. As an alternative to the increasing oppositio n between the public and private spheres, between state and free enterprise, it proved that there could be business and pro� t in supplyin g public services. But everything has a price. Rather than obliterating the worst of socialism and replacing it by the best of liberalism , it seems that as far as social justice is concerned, the ‘third way’ has replaced the best part of socialism , distributiv e justice, by the worst part of liberalism , the survival of the � ttest. Acknowledgements The author is grateful to Michael Freeden and two anonymous referees of this journal, to Kees van Kersbergen, Grahame Lock, and Anna van der Vleuten at the Faculty of Policy Sciences, and to members of the Chinese Academy of Social Sciences, for their most helpful comments. Notes and references 1. S. Buckler and D. Dolowitz, ‘Theorizing the third way: New Labour and social justice’, Journal of Political Ideologies, 5/3 (2000), pp. 301–320. 2. A. Blair and G. Schröder, Europe: The Third Way/Die Neue Mitte (www.labour.org.uk , 1999). 3. A. Giddens, The Third Way (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1998); A. Giddens, The Third Way and its Critics (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2000). 4. Buckler and Dolowitz, op. cit., Ref. 1, p. 305. 5. Buckler and Dolowitz, ibid., p. 307. 6. Blair and Schröder, op. cit., Ref. 2. 7. J. B. Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1971), p. 538. 8. Buckler and Dolowitz, op. cit., Ref. 1, p. 309. 9. Rawls, op. cit., Ref. 7, p. 9. 10. Rawls, ibid., p. 103. 11. Buckler and Dolowitz, op. cit., Ref. 1, p. 308. 12. J. B. Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), p. 13. 13. Buckler and Dolowitz, op. cit., Ref. 1, pp. 309, 311. 14. Buckler and Dolowitz, ibid., p. 313. 15. Buckler and Dolowitz, ibid., pp. 310–311. 16. Cf. Rawls, op. cit., Ref. 7, p. 108. 17. M. Wissenburg, Imperfection and Impartiality (London: UCL Press, 1999). 235 work_gzuyb2jfk5av7haxtga32aud4e ---- HARAMAYA LAW REVIEW Vol. 6 (2017) ISSN: 2227-2178 (P) & 2305-3739 (E) [29] To cite this article: Aberra Degefa Nagawo, Beyond the Individualization of Punishment: Reflections on the Borana Oromo’s Collective Criminal Responsibility, HARAMAYA LAW REVIEW 6 (2017): 29-42 ____________________ BEYOND THE INDIVIDUALIZATION OF PUNISHMENT: REFLECTIONS ON THE BORANA OROMO’S COLLECTIVE CRIMINAL RESPONSIBILITY Aberra Degefa Nagawo Abstract The article mainly looks at the role collective responsibility plays in the prevention of crime among the Borana Oromo of Ethiopia. Borana is a clan-based society where every member of a clan enjoys privileges and is given protection by his (her) clan. The clan provides support to its member when it is needed, and assumes responsibility when a member commits crime. If a member of a clan commits homicide, Guma is paid by the perpetrator’s clan to the clan from which a member has been killed. The objective of this article is to examine the underlying philosophy for the principle of collective responsibility and the merits of the principle in preventing crime among the Borana. The philosophy differs from that of the formal criminal justice system, where crime is individualized and the individual is answerable for the crime he commits. The article is based on the interviews the author has made from 2012-2014 with Borana elders during fieldwork to the area and review of the relevant literature. As it is part of the cultural values of the society and suitable for the clan- based and pastoralist Borana society, the practice of collective responsibility cannot easily be dismissed by forcibly imposing individual responsibility. Keywords: Borana, clan, collective responsibility, crime, Guma I. INTRODUCTION Social norms and disputes are as old as human society. Every human society has norms which regulates relations of its members. Long before the emergence of the modern state and its formal justice system, human society had normative rules, procedures and institutions through which they resolved all their disputes. In the process of resolving disputes, the main parties involved were the disputants and the community within which wrongs have been committed. Previously, states had no role in settlement of disputes including crime. Dispute settlement was the property of the society which the state has stolen at a certain point in human history.1  Aberra Degefa (PhD) is an Assistant Professor at School of Law, Addis Ababa University. He has LLB, LLM and PhD from Addis Ababa University. He has Post-Graduate Diploma from ISS, The Hague. His areas of research interest include Constitutional law, Legal Pluralism and Indigenous Justice System. 1 Nill Christie, Conflicts as Property, 17(1) BRITISH JOURNAL OF CRIMINOLOGY (1977) 1-15. 30 HARAMAYA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 6:2017] With the emergence of the modern state and its formal criminal justice system, the stakeholders lost their control over the justice process and the outcome. Under the formal state criminal justice system, the earlier authority and roles of the society in the settlements of criminal dispute disappeared and replaced by the state. But even if states have taken the monopoly of settling criminal disputes, in significant parts of the world, some indigenous societies have continued to settle their own disputes informally based on their own customary laws.2 In many parts of Africa and the world, these informal justice systems and their corresponding dispute resolution processes are still operating along the formal justice systems.3 The norms regulating the dispute processes are rooted in the communal values of the people. When a certain wrong is committed, it is not only personal relationship but also community harmony that is disrupted.4 For this reason, dispute resolution aims at restoring the communal relationships disrupted by the wrongful act.5 As religion, law and culture are interwoven, it is quite difficult to separately look at the law.6 In order to know the African approach to criminal dispute resolution system, one needs to understand the peoples’ worldview and the social setting within which each African society is placed and interact. Worldview is described as “mental lenses that are entrenched ways of perceiving the world.”7 African people have their own indigenous worldviews that shape their perception of the world and human relationships. What gave rise to these indigenous worldviews are their close relationships and interactions with their environment. Since the assumptions, decisions and modes of problem solving in a given society are influenced by their worldviews, any study concerning a community would require proper understanding of the target community’s worldview.8 Without proper understanding of the worldview of a certain people, the judgment we make about the practices among a certain people will not be sound. African indigenous worldviews are holistic, local and oral in their characteristics. Africans view knowledge itself as holistic, cyclic, and dependent upon relationships and connections to living and non-living beings and entities.9 In many indigenous communities, harmony and peace are looked at not only as harmony between human beings but it extends to harmony with nature. In Africa, family ties, kinship relation and community networking are constantly respected, 2 Ewa Wojkowska, Doing Justice: How Informal justice can Contribute, UNDP-Oslo, Governance Centre, 2006. 3 PENAL REFORM INTERNATIONAL, ACCESS TO JUSTICE IN SUB SAHARAN AFRICA: THE ROLE OF TRADITIONAL AND INFORMAL JUSTICE SYSTEMS, London. Astron Printers (2000). 4 H Driberg, The African Conception of law, JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE LEGISLATION AND INTERNATIONAL LAW, Third Series 16(4) (1934) Retrieved on November 10, 2014 from http://www.jstor.org/stable/753856 5 R.B.G. Choudree, Traditions of Conflict Resolution in South Africa, AFRICA JOURNAL ON CONFLICT RESOLUTION, 1:1 (1999). 6 L. A. Ayinia, African Philosophy of Law: A Critique, 6 JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL AND COMPARATIVE LAW, 147 (2002) 7 Michael Anthony Hart, Indigenous Worlds Views, Knowledge and research: The Development of an Indigenous research paradigm, JOURNAL OF INDIGENOUS VOICES IN SOCIAL WORK, 1(1) 2010, at 2. 8 Idowu William, Against the Sceptical argument and the absence thesis: African Jurisprudence and the Challenges of Positivist Historiography, THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY, SCIENCE & LAW, 6(2): 9-24 (2006). 9 Carol A. Hand, Judith Hunks & Toni House. Restorative Justice: The Indigenous justice system, CONTEMPORARY JUSTICE REVIEW: ISSUES IN CRIMINAL, SOCIAL, AND RESTORATIVE JUSTICE, 15(4) 449-467 (2012), DOI:10.1080/10282580.2012.734576. http://www.jstor.org/stable/753856 Aberra, INDIVIDUALIZATION OF PUNISHMENT 31 maintained and strengthened. This strong belief in collectiveness is an indication of the centrality of communal life with emphasis on interconnectedness and relationships.10 The attitude of togetherness and the spirit of humanity are universal values embedded in African indigenous worldviews. As stated by Steve Biko, We [Africans] regard our living together not as an unfortunate mishap warranting endless competition among us but as a deliberate act of God to make us a community of brothers and sisters jointly involved in the quest for a composite answer to the varied problems of life. Hence, in all we do, we always place man first and hence all our action is usually joint or community-oriented action rather than the individualism which is the hallmark of capitalist approach.11 According to Biko, rather than self-centered individual competition, what governs traditional African way of life is collectiveness and spirit of harmony. In their daily interactions and relationships, Africans are guided by their indigenous norms and values which is an integral part of their worldviews. Belief in consensus, dialogue, inclusion, reciprocity, fairness and mutual trust are the core values of African societies.12 In most traditional African societies, social relationships and harmony are given prime attention. A criminal dispute settlement process usually involves relatives of the victim, the offender and the community. The immediate objective of a criminal dispute resolution is to mend the broken or damaged relationship and repair wrongs, and restore community harmony. In Ethiopia itself, there are societies with their own indigenous justice systems settling disputes based on their own customary laws. Borana Oromo is one such society where disputes including criminal disputes are settled by indigenous justice system.13 The Borana have their indigenous dispute resolution system which is operating along the formal justice system without formal recognition. This has given rise to the co-existence of two competing justice systems. Because of lack of recognition and defined relationship, the two systems have uneasy relationship which is having its own impact on the people of the area. Under Borana indigenous justice system, clan members are collectively liable for the harm one of their members caused to a victim by way of paying Gumaa which is made in the forms of heads of cattle or sum of money. Among the Borana what applies is the principle of collective responsibility which is opposed to the dominant Western principle of criminal justice which makes only the individual offender responsible for a crime. When looked at from the viewpoint of the formal criminal justice system, the principle applied among the Borana is considered collective punishment for a crime committed by an 10 A Melton ‘Indigenous justice systems and Tribal society’, Accessed 29th April 2011 from http://aidainc.net/Publications/ij_systems.htm 11 STEVE BIKO, I WRITE WHAT I LIKE: A SELECTION OF HIS WRITINGS, Heinemann (1987), at 42. 12 J.H. Driberg, The African Conception of Law, JOURNAL OF COMPARATIVE LEGISLATION AND INTERNATIONAL LAW, 16(4) 230-245 (1934) available at http://www.jstor.org/stable/753856; Ada Pecos Melton, Indigenous Justice Systems and Tribal Society, in WANDA D. MCCASLIN, ED., JUSTICE AS HEALING: INDIGENOUS WAYS. WRITINGS ON COMMUNITY PEACE-MAKING AND RESTORATIVE JUSTICE FROM THE NATIVE LAW CENTRE. St. Paul, MN: Living Justice Press. (2005), at 108-120. 13 ALULA PANKHURST & GETACHEW ASEFFA (EDS) GRASS ROOTS JUSTICE IN ETHIOPIA: THE CONTRIBUTION OF CUSTOMARY DISPUTE RESOLUTION, Addis Ababa, French Center of Ethiopian Studies, (2008). http://aidainc.net/Publications/ij_systems.htm 32 HARAMAYA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 6:2017] individual. Rules, institutions and systems in different societies are created by the particular societies to address their own specific problems. If such systems are user-friendly and responsive to the needs of the particular people, imposing an alien system would harm the society. This article aims at exploring the merits of the principle of collective criminal responsibility which is being used among the Borana in the context of Borana society. It tries to investigate how this system has helped in preventing crime within the Borana social setting. To meet its aim, the study is conducted based on qualitative data gathered from Borana elders during the author’s PhD field work between 2012 to 2014. The data were gathered through interviews and focus group discussions with Borana elders. In addition, interviews were conducted with individuals in the justice sector, prisoners and victims of crime. Further information was also gathered by consulting the relevant literature to deal with the merits of collective criminal responsibility as it is being practiced among the Borana. The remaining parts of the article are organized as follows. Section II looks at Borana indigenous worldview and how the indigenous justice system works. The principle of collective criminal responsibility as applied among the Borana is presented under Section III. Finally, section IV provides conclusion and remarks on the subject. II. BORANA WORLDVIEW AND INDIGENOUS JUSTICE SYSTEM Borana is located in the southern part of Ethiopia in Oromia National Regional State. Although, Borana is one of the administrative zones of the National Regional State of Oromia, Borana people also inhabit other neighboring zones of the region. While Borana and Guji Oromo constitute the majority in the zone, other minorities include the Gabra, Burji and Garri.14 Borana people are largely pastoral where the livelihood of the people is based on pastoralism. In Borana social system, the entire society is divided into two exogamous moieties known as Sabo and Gona. The two moieties are further subdivided into clans and sub-clans. Among the Borana, clans share collective rights and obligations. Clan members settle their disputes peacefully at clan assemblies and help one another in times of hardship. The clan elders (hayyus) have the responsibility of settling disputes and imposing sanctions on those who commit wrongful act.15 A. Borana Oromo Worldview Without proper understanding of Borana worldview that shapes the entire Borana way of life and their interactions with one another and the natural world, it is difficult to understand their philosophy as applied to problem of crime and its consequences. The defining feature of Borana worldview is harmony and solidarity between human beings, nature and God. Among the Oromo in general, there is a strong belief that human beings and the natural environment are interconnected and live together in a relationship of harmony. As they believe in the reciprocal relationships and interdependence between human beings and nature, the Borana Oromo give high respect for the cosmic order put in place by Waaqa (God). They take care of all forms of 14 TOM LEUS & CYNTHIA SALVADORI, AADAA BOORANA: A DICTIONARY OF OROMO CULTURE, Addis Ababa Shama Books, (2006) 15 MARCO BASSI, DECISION IN THE SHADE, POLITICAL AND JUDICIAL PROCESSES AMONG THE OROMO-BORANA. Asmara: The Red Sea Press, 2005. Aberra, INDIVIDUALIZATION OF PUNISHMENT 33 life; they never mistreat any form of life.16 The indigenous religion of the Oromo is known as Waaqeffanna. This indigenous Oromo religion is centered around Waaqa, who among the Oromo is considered the Creator of the universe and the sustainer of all life on earth.17 According to Oromo holistic view of cosmic order, Waaqa has placed everything in a well- balanced order. In their view, it is only by being in harmony with each other and with nature that they get the blessing of Waaqa. They all believe that any human act that disturbs the cosmic and social order is an infringement of the laws of Waaqa which would bring danger to the wrongdoer, his relatives and the community. In the context of human relationship, Oromo holistic view plays significant role in maintaining social peace and harmony. In giving recognition to interconnectedness of lives of human beings, the worldview establishes a necessary check and balance to human relations.18 In terms of regulating human relationships, an important moral value that is an integral part of Oromo worldview is the concept of safuu (moral rules). Safuu is a moral standard that is based on Oromo notions of distance and respect for all things. It is a standard which helps to judge social taboo and deplorable habits.19 The moral and ethical obligations embodied in safuu are guides for the respect of the creator and all creatures (Uuma and Uumama). Human actions or inactions are founded on safuu which directs everyone on the right path. The underlying philosophy of safuu is that everything has a role to play and natural right to exist. Oromo understanding of what is wrong and right in human interactions is drawn from their holistic and relational worldview.20 The ways they deal with problems are also shaped by the same relational worldview. One very strong moral bond that unites the Borana is the concept of Boorantitti reflected in “peaceful well–being, unselfishness and respect for a common law.”21 In Borana social life, “the ideology of Boorantitti demands that all conflicts between Borana should be solved peacefully and the maintenance of internal peace is a strongly expressed ideal.”22 Every Borana grows up with full awareness of the supreme value of the ideology of Boorantittii and nagaa Boorana. Nagaa Boorana is the governing philosophy of Borana social relations. Nagaa Boorana refers to the orderly running of all relations, interactions and the non-violent settlement of disputes and conflict while Boorantittii refers to the feeling of commonality each Borana will have for one 16 Workneh Qalbessa, Traditional Oromo Studies towards the Environment: an Argument for Environmentally Sound development, SOCIAL SCIENCE RESEARCH REPORT SERIES, number 19. Addis Ababa: OSSREA (2001). 17 LAMBERT BARTELS, OROMO RELIGION: MYTHS AND RITES OF THE WESTERN OROMO OF ETHIOPIA, Berlin, 1983 18 Id. 19 Gemechu Megerssa, The Oromo Worldview, JOURNAL OF OROMO STUDIES 12 (1&2) 68-79, 2005 20 Dejene Gemechu, Conflict and Conflict Resolution Among the Woliso Oromo of eastern Macha, with particular emphasis on the Guma, Addis Ababa, United Printers (2007) 21 Gufu Oba, Shifting Identities along Resource Borders: Becoming and continuing to be Borana Oromo in P.T.W BAXTER, J HULTIN, AND TRIULZI (EDS.), BEING AND BECOMING OROMO: HISTORICAL AND ANTHROPOLOGICAL ENQUIRIES, 117-132, Asmara: Red sea Press, (1996) at 120. The Borana common law is their Aada Seera which is the embodiment of all their laws. 22 Johan Helland, Institutional Erosion in the Dry Lands: The Case of the Borana Pastoralists, EASTERN AFRICA SOCIAL SCIENCE RESEARCH REVIEW (EASSREA), 14(2): 49-73, (1998) at 64. 34 HARAMAYA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 6:2017] another. The maintenance of nagaa Boorana is the core value that guides the actions of both the spiritual and political institutions in Borana.23 The duty of Abba Gadaa and clan elders (hayyus) at every level is to maintain peace and harmony among the Borana. 24 Nagaa is a pervasive and sustained concern in the daily life of every Borana and the daily blessings given by Borana elders are prayers of peace.25 Borana conception of peace is holistic, relational and collective. Relationships of harmony among members and with the environment are central features in Borana conception of peace and justice. Among the Borana, peace is viewed as a collective value and disruption of this value will have collective harm. The Borana believe that a certain wrongful act disrupts the social harmony within a community. In their view, re-establishment of the disrupted peace would require collective response.26 The Borana view their Waaqa as the source and guardian of peace and truth. When a wrong- doer violates Borana aada-seera, he does not only disrupt nagaa Boorana which is extremely valued by the Borana as a community, but he would also offend Waaqa who is the God of peace (Waaqa mufachiise).27 The totality of Borana normative system is known as aada-seera referring to a sacred and profane set of laws governing behavior and maintenance of peace and order in Borana society.28 Every Borana comes to know and understands aada-seera through his daily experience as a way of life.29 A wrong-doer faces not only public condemnation but also possible punishment of Waaqa. This fear of possible condemnation of the community and Waaqa’s punishment has helped to curb crime among the Borana. The Borana have developed strong moral standards which helped them cultivate and maintain the ideology of Boorantittii and regulate their behavior towards one another. As an individual, in the daily interactions, every Borana should refrain from saying words that spoil relationships with others. The common saying among the Borana is, “nageenyi fuula arrabnni abba oole oolti.”30 This literally means ‘peace follows our tongue’: what we verbally express during our daily interactions with others. If a person makes a statement or utters a word that spoils relationship with others in the daily interaction, it will disrupt harmony. B. Borana Indigenous Justice System The Borana have an indigenous governance system known as Gada. The system is an all- embracing governance system which has been regulating the political, legal, juridical and 23 ASMAROM LEGESSE, OROMO DEMOCRACY: AN INDIGENOUS AFRICAN POLITICAL SYSTEM, Red Sea Press, Asmara (2000). 24 Borbor Bule, Interview made in Aug 1, 2013. 25 Every assembly begins and ends with blessings and prayer of peace. I have observed this during the 40th Gumii Gaayyo Assembly in 2012. 26 BASSI, supra note 15. 27 Borbor Bule, Interview made August 1, 2013 28 E. Watson, Interinstitutional alliances and Conflicts in natural resources management: Preliminary Research findings from Borana, Oromia Region, Ethiopia, Marena research Project Working Paper no 4 (2001). 29 There are clan elders or Hayyus who know all the laws. Besides, most of these laws are discussed every eight years on the Gumii Gaayyo where every participant has the opportunity to know them. Surely, it is also through intergenerational transference of knowledge. 30 Jaatanii Diida, Interview made July 30, 2013. Aberra, INDIVIDUALIZATION OF PUNISHMENT 35 economic aspects of the Borana people.31 Gada is an age-grade class system that succeeds each other every eight years in assuming economic, political and social responsibilities. One age-set rules for eight years before handing over to the next younger age-set. A complete Gada cycle consists of five age-grades. The roles and rules attached to the age-grade system is the most important element that regulates Gada system. Borana Gada governance system is built in such a way as to enable all members of the society to learn and to carry out their duties at different stages of their lives and careers.32 Gada system has strong institutional structure with linkages from the Abba Gada at the top, down to the village levels. The Abba Gada is elected from one of the two Borana moieties with his team of advisors. The governing power under Borana Gada system is decentralized and vested in the assemblies at various levels. At the apex of all the assemblies is Gumii Gaayyo which is a pan–Borana assembly drawn from representatives of all Borana clans. Gumii refers to the general assembly and Gaayyo to the place where the assembly gathers. The assembly takes place every eight years mid-point within one Gada period. Gumii Gaayyo has supreme authority on all important matters like lawmaking and enforcement. Every eight years, the Gumii proclaims new laws, amend the old ones, and evaluate the Abba Gada. As a supreme judicial body, the Gumii resolves disputes referred to it which could not be resolved at lower levels. No other Borana authority can reverse decisions made by Gumii Gaayyo. Borana people have indigenous laws known as aada seera (customary laws). These laws are made by Gumi Gaayyo and amended by the same body. The executive authority in Borana is entrusted to Adulaa Council elders who are six in number. Three each are drawn from Sabo and Gona moieties. As a legitimate leadership of the Borana, the Adulaa Council is responsible for upholding nagaa and aada (peace and custom) of Borana. The Adulaa Council administers all Borana affairs based on laws and customs of Borana aada seera, which is made and modified only by Gumii Gaayyo. The Abba Gada heads the Adulaa Council and with his team of council members, he is responsible for the eight year period.33 Like most African societies, the same collectivist and holistic worldview is prevalent among the Borana Oromo of Ethiopia. Oromo indigenous worldview is an expression of Oromo values and their perception of the world. Oromo worldview is holistic and collectivist in its approach to social problems and ways of solving these problems. The Borana conception of peace (nagaa) goes beyond harmony between human beings and extends to harmony with nature. Their collectivist approach to problem of crime has been shaped by their holistic and collectivist worldview. This collective approach of the Borana has evolved from their local experiences and is part of their indigenous knowledge systems which makes it more suitable in addressing local problems including crimes. 31 ASMAROM LEGESSE, GADA: THREE APPROACHES TO THE STUDY OF AFRICAN SOCIETY. London: The Free Press, (1973). 32 BASSI, supra note 15. 33 E. Watson, Interinstitutional alliances and conflicts in natural resources management: Preliminary research findings from Borana, Oromia Region, Ethiopia Maren research Project Working Paper no 4 (2001) 36 HARAMAYA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 6:2017] The Borana have their indigenous dispute resolution system which is operating along the formal justice system without formal recognition. This has given rise to the co-existence of two competing justice systems. Because of lack of recognition and defined relationship, the two systems have uneasy relationship which is having its own impact on the people of the area. Under Borana indigenous justice system, clan members are collectively liable for the harm one of their members caused to a victim by way of paying Gumaa which is made in the forms of heads of cattle or sum of money. Among the Borana what applies is the principle of collective responsibility which is opposed to the dominant Western principle of criminal justice which makes only the individual offender responsible for a crime. When looked at from the viewpoint of the formal criminal justice system, the principle applied among the Borana is considered collective punishment for a crime committed by an individual. Rules, institutions and systems in different societies are created by the particular societies to address their own specific problems. If such systems are user-friendly and responsive to the needs of the particular people, imposing an alien system would harm the society. This article will try to show the relevance of this principle still being used among the Borana in their specific setting. Borana indigenous justice system embraces the laws and institutions which serve as a framework for settlement of all disputes.34 The Oromo Gada system ascribes great value to the rule of law. Under Oromo indigenous Gada democracy, since law is considered supreme, no one is above the law. The Borana say “Seerri laafaaf kaa’an jabaa hinhaanqatu” which in short means ‘everyone is equal before the law’.35 In their long history of self- administration, one important value that has been maintained by the Borana is respect for the rule of law. According to Asmarom Legesse “the Oromo are one of the most orderly legalistic societies in black Africa and many of their laws are consciously crafted rules, not customarily evolved habits.”36 There is a strong belief among the Borana that any act that disrupts Borana interconnectedness and harmony poses a danger to nagaa Boorana and erode the ideology of Boorantitti.37 Borana indigenous justice system has indigenous dispute resolution mechanism and institutions of justice and reconciliation that are operating and coexist along the formal Ethiopian criminal justice system. Since the formal justice system has exclusive authority over criminal matters, Borana indigenous justice system handles criminal cases without formal recognition. The Borana have effective indigenous laws for the use of common range resources like wells and pasture.38 The Oromo in general strongly believe that social justice and equal benefit from natural resources cannot be maintained in the absence of rule of law.39 34 Like in other indigenous African societies, Borana laws don’t have classification into criminal and civil laws. 35 Badajaa Waariyoo, Interview made July 28, 2013. 36 Asmarom, supra note 23, at 29. 37 Kanu Jilo, Interview made on July 31, 2013. 38 BASSI, supra note 15. 39 DIRRIBI DEMISSIE, OROMO WISDOM IN BLACK CIVILISATION, Finfinnee Print. & Pub. Finfinne (Addis Ababa) 2011. Aberra, INDIVIDUALIZATION OF PUNISHMENT 37 The main objective of Borana indigenous justice system is to ensure nagaa Boorana through effective regulation of relations among the people.40 The social harmony and collective identity of Borana people is ensured by their aadaa-Seera. Since litigation is detested, disputes are rare among the Borana.41 Besides, in view of the fact that every day greetings constitute a form of preaching peace, a “sustained feud between groups or individuals is unacceptable” in Oromo society.42 According to the interviews with the justice officers of Borana Zone drawn from the judiciary, public prosecutors, police and prison and corrective centers, disputes and crimes were frequent around urban areas like Yaballo, Moyale, Bule Hora and the highland areas where there is farming.43 The Borana are socially tied together by kinship relations in that everyone is connected to one of the Borana clans by which he identifies himself. How the Borana behave and address their problems is determined by the kinship relationship and interconnected nature of the society. In view of the fact that Borana people are largely pastoral and significant resources are collectively used, the clan system serves as an important structure through which wealth distribution among clan members is made. Important communal activities of clans include digging, maintenance and regulation of wells and other sources of water. Clans also play a key role in ritual performance, regulation of water resources and in the election of political leaders. Within his own clan, everyone has obligations toward one another. Failing to discharge one’s obligation towards a clan or fellow Borana would spoil the mutually supportive relation established by Boorana aada- seera.44 III. COLLECTIVE SANCTION (RESPONSIBILITY) A. Collective Sanction-Exclusion from Nagaa Boorana Collective sanction may result from two situations. One is when a Borana violates Borana aada- seera and fails to carry the penalty imposed on him by elders at clan and Borana levels. The other sanction is the one imposed collectively on a clan whose member has committed a crime like homicide. When a Borana defies Borana aada–seera and disregards decisions given by elders, the case will be brought before Gumii Gaayyo where his exclusion from nagaa Boorana will be announced.45Gumii Gaayyo is a supreme body with a supreme governing power which is 40 Badajaa Waariyoo, Interview made July 28, 2013. 41 In an interview I have made with Borbor Bule on August 1, 2013, since land and pasture are collectively used and regulated by the community, the causes for criminal disputes between individuals are minimal. In one of my observations during my visit to Dirre district in May 2014, I have been to Dubuluq town on a big market day where there was a single police in the town who as he told me went there from Yaballo for that day. There are no police stations in the Pastoral areas. 42 Mamo Hebo, The Role of elders in conflict Resolution: The Case of arsi Oromo with Special reference to Dodola District and its Environments, in TAREKEGN ADEBO & HANNAH TSADIK (EDS.), MAKING PEACE IN ETHIOPIA: FIVE CASES OF TRADITIONAL MECHANISMS FOR CONFLICT RESOLUTION, pp 48-77 Addis Ababa: peace and development committee, 2008, at 48. 43 Interviews were made on February, 23, 2012, Aug 23, 2012, and July 24, 2013 With the Zonal Justice Bureau Officer (T.A.), Public Prosecutor (M.G) and Police Officer (T.L). 44 BASSI, supra note 15. 45 The exclusion includes denial of greetings. 38 HARAMAYA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 6:2017] subordinate only to divine rule. It is organized every eight years and made up of all the Gada assemblies of the Borana clans. Legislative power on all matters concerning Borana is vested in the Gumii Gaayyo. In addition to legislative power; Gumii Gaayyo has political and juridical powers.46 A person brought before the Gumii will lose all Borana privileges attached to Boorantitti which will make him defenseless. The formal way of depriving a disruptive person his Boorantitti identity is by excluding him from nagaa Borana at Gumii Gaayyo. As a result of the exclusion, the law-breaker will be excommunicated from the community where every Borana will withhold greetings and blessings from him. Most importantly, the habitual offender will be deprived of all social privileges and ritual support required from the whole Borana. In their justice system, the Borana bring habitual law-breakers into line simply by withdrawing all the social privileges, benefits and ritual support required from the whole Borana including the daily greetings, blessings and the prayers of the Borana. At the 40th Gumii Gaayo, which took place in August 2012, a person who has raped a girl and defied the authority of the Gada was brought before the Gumii and he was cursed for the act and defiance.47 The act of the young person was described by the Abba Gadaa as a detestable and disruptive of nagaa Boorana. He considered the act as unacceptable under Borana aada- seera which required the decision of the Gumii.48 After hearing the case from the Abbaa Gadaa, Gumii members discussed on the issue and finally decided to exclude the young person from nagaa Boorana. Since, having known about his son’s criminal act, the father failed to advise his son to respect the law; he was also excluded from nagaa Boorana. According to Borana aadaa- seera, if a person harbors a criminal or advises him not to appear before elders, his act is considered against the law for which he will be punished. Based on the exclusion declared by the 40th Gumii Gaayo, the young person and his father will not be looked for if they are lost; they will not be buried, if they die. No one will marry their daughters nor does any person give them his daughter. They will be deprived of the right to use water-wells (eela) belonging to Borana clans. No one should enter their houses and sit on the seats they provide. The Gumii declared that the exclusion will apply to any Borana who violates the exclusion imposed on the young person and his father. If any person violates the exclusion by allowing them to use a water-well, that person will also face the same exclusion. As a result of the exclusion from nagaa Boorana, the young person and his father have been deprived of Booranntitti and all the privileges and benefits derived from it. In May 2014, the young person asked for forgiveness as a result of which his Borana rights and privileges have been restored. In Borana pastoral way of life, watering of animals, herding, sharing of goods and services and settlement of disputes dictates mutual support and collaboration.49 In Borana social setting, where everything required for livelihood including water is collectively used and administered 46 A Shongolo, The Gumii Gaayyo assembly of the Boran: A traditional legislative organ and its relationship to the Ethiopian state and a modernizing worlds, Zeschcrift fur ethnologie 119 (1996). 47 I have personally observed this. 48 Abbaa Gadaa Guyyo Goba interview made on Aug 20, 2012 49 Jaatanii, Interview made May 14, 2014. Aberra, INDIVIDUALIZATION OF PUNISHMENT 39 through clan system, a habitual offender who may possibly be subjected to such withdrawal cannot survive. A person who violates rules having to do with the use of water resources will be punished by exclusion from using that water resource (eela) which is used collectively by all clan members. If a person repeatedly violates the rules, he will be deprived of access to these collectively used water resources and excluded from all vital social supports.50 In that context, the kind of sanction imposed on the young person and his father at the 40th Gumii Gaayo can be considered a very severe punishment. In a pastoral society, withdrawal of social support and exclusion from access to dry season water wells means the impossibility of carrying out the traditional pastoral activity. Among the pastoral Borana, even a basic work like the extraction of water from the deep traditional wells requires the cooperation of numerous pastoral units. That is why clans share collective rights and obligations and clan members help one another in times of hardship. Through his clan, a person can be coerced to fulfill his obligations towards his clan and fellow Borana. Each Borana clan is clustered into lineages which is an important subdivision of a clan with a considerable influence on the life of individual Borana. The social privileges, rights, duties, seniority position, and social identity of a person are rooted in the lineage. In addition to being an effective way of reaching him in Borana land, in times of crisis, a person’s clan and lineage comes to his rescue.51 Among the Borana, an individual who disrupts nagaa Boorana by repeatedly infringing Borana aada-seera is considered as a person lacking the character of Boorantitti.52 If a Borana disregards his obligations towards his clan and fellow Borana by repeatedly disobeying Borana aada –seera, the clan will withdraw all the benefits and privileges the habitual offender enjoys. Such a person is outlawed by his clan and deprived of his status where he can no more claim clan protection. The clan to which such an offender belongs disowns him and discontinues all further responsibility for his criminal actions.53 B. Gumaa - A Practice of Collective Responsibility Borana aada-seera has put in place punishment (adaba) that is effective by way of inducing obedience and enabling members of the society to maintain a strong sense of discipline. Under Borana indigenous justice system, the clan whose member has committed serious crime like homicide will be collectively responsible for the criminal act committed by such a member. Through such collectivist sanctions, the Borana have created a mechanism of containing crime where every clan as a collective and every individual member make sure that laws are respected by way of refraining from committing crime. The system has been found to be appropriate for the kinship-based Borana pastoral way of life.54 50 Borbor Bule, Interview made on Aug 1, 2013. 51 Asmarom, supra note 23. 52 Jaatanii, Interview made on Aug 3, 2013. 53 Gufu, supra note 21. 54 P.T.W Baxter, Borana Age-Sets and Generation-Sets: Gada, A Puzzle or a Maze, in P.T.W BAXTER & URI ALMAGOR (EDS.) AGE, GENERATION AND TIME (pp. 151-182) London (1978). 40 HARAMAYA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 6:2017] The common practice among the Borana is, when homicide takes place, the killer will immediately report the incident to his near relatives and he will be kept at a certain temporary sanctuary. No Borana clan gives shelter to a culprit or a Borana who has spilled Borana blood with a view to hide him from justice. A culprit will be sheltered until the victim’s relatives are approached and araara process begins. The araara process commences with the family of the offender, with the help of elders, immediately approaching the relatives of the victim and asking for araara so as to avoid revenge. The araara ritual requires that the wrong-doer verbally express his remorse to the victim’s relatives. This will remove the feuds (warra gumaa) between the relatives of the victim and the offender thus bringing the araara process to its consummation.55 ‘Booranni nama ajeese gumaa oso hinbaasin of kessa hinkaa’u. Dhignni namaa dhangala’e sun lammii sana xureessa. Kanaafu gumaa fi hooda baafachu qaba.’56 This means, among the Borana, a clan does not keep or hide a person who has spilt human blood and has not gone through the reconciliation ritual and paid gumaa since doing that would bring from God a certain misfortune to that community. The belief among the Borana is, in case of homicide, the killer’s act violates not only Booranaa aadaa-seera but also the law of Waaqa. As a consequence, the clan to which the perpetrator belongs will collectively be disposed to spiritual retribution from Waaqa. Adabbi Waaqa hambisuuf nama qoffatti oso hintaane Waaqatti araaramuutu barbaachisa.57 This literally means, in order to escape God’s punishment, you need to make reconciliation not only with man but with God as well. For this reason, the Borana consider both the payment of gumaa and the araara compulsory. From the offender’s perspective, based on Borana collectivist philosophy and aadaa-seera, clan members enjoy privileges and benefits deriving from their membership which includes giving a member protection and coming to his rescue when a clan member is in need of support. This indigenous principle of collective responsibility applied among the Borana may be viewed as a practice that encourages criminality. Because if one knows that his/her clan is going to be responsible for his act, he will tend to commit crime. However, the Borana argue otherwise. They say “Gosti sodaa kaffalti yakka irra of eegee, wal’eega.”58 This means the clans restrain their members from committing crime for fear of paying gumaa. Besides, as intentional killing is not acceptable among the Borana, the payment of Gumaa is limited to cases where the killing is accidental (Dagu).59 In case of a clan member who has intentionally killed a Borana and that is proved, the clan will not be responsible for that.60 These days, such cases are left to the court to be dealt with. 55 Dirribii, supra note 39. 56 Waaqo Guyyo, Interview made on July 30, 2013. 57 Jaatanii Diida, Interview made on May 14, 2014. 58 Borbor Bule, Interview made on Aug 1, 2013. 59 Actually, from what I have gathered from the elders, dagu is much broader than accidental. The elders who see the case will determine whether it is dagu or intentional killing. 60 Rape, serious bodily injuries and spilling of human blood are punishable but what is paid may vary. The Borana have laws for everything and what the punishments are for the wrongs committed against another person and even horses. Accidental killing cannot be prevented but the belief and the moral restraint among the society is preventative effect. Aberra, INDIVIDUALIZATION OF PUNISHMENT 41 According to Borana elders, supporting a clan member who intentionally killed a person would be encouraging killing. Since this is known, everyone refrains from intentionally committing crime. Besides, in terms of material costs, since repeated crimes will be too great a strain on the resource of a clan, every clan will see to it that all members comply with Boorana aada-seera. If there is a clan member who repeatedly commits crime, the clan to which the habitual offender belongs withdraws all the privileges and benefits such member enjoys and excludes him from nagaa Boorana. 61 As violation of aada-seera is detested under Borana indigenous justice system, there is no room for criminals. Clans restrain their members from committing crime in fear of paying gumaa.62 As an individual, every Borana comply with Borana laws in fear of being deprived of the privileges and protection flowing from membership which in effect has made the Borana generally law-abiding. According to Asmarom, “how deep the sense of order is among the Borana can be gleaned from the fact that homicide-within their society is virtually unknown.”63 In Borana society, the principle of collective responsibility is serving as an effective instrument through which the individual Borana and the collective mutually ensure obedience to Boorana aada-seera, prevent crime and consequently avoid payment of gumaa. The principle has enabled the pastoral Borana to collectively control those who may possibly disrupt their social harmony (nagaa Boorana).64 The formal criminal justice system has imposed itself on the Borana people and claims to be the best protector of Borana peace.65 As a whole, the philosophy of collective responsibility among the Borana views crime as having communal character. They do not consider crime as a mere solitary act of an individual which has nothing to do with the community. The Borana look at the causes, consequences and remedies of crime in collective sense. In actual fact, the merits of a certain practice are measured by its responsiveness to the needs of the users of the system. IV. CONCLUSION Communal way of life is the bedrock of African indigenous worldview. Africans measure the effectiveness of their laws and sanctions by their ability to maintain communal harmony. The fact that Borana people are largely pastoralists has shaped their values, rules and institutional set up. Borana is a kinship society where a member of a clan enjoys benefits and privileges as a member of a clan. A clan will provide the necessary support and protection to a law-abiding clan member where he faces hardship and attack. But a Borana who disregards his obligations 61 Borbor Bule, Interview made on May 16, 2014. 62 A person who commits crime is a liability to a clan so in order to avoid this liability, clans want to make sure that every clan and clan member comply with Borana laws. 63 Asmarom, supra note 23, at 27. 64 The only prisons in Borana are in Yaballo and Bule Hora. In places where this practice is effectively working, there are police stations. I met a single policeman at Dubuluq on a market day. 65 The formal justice system is inaccessible to Borana pastoral areas. They are limited to the big towns and the Zonal capital Yaballo. Besides, a Zonal police officer I have interviewed has told me that they don’t have police stations in the lowland pastoral woredas (Interview with T. L July 24, 2013). The same thing is true of other formal justice institutions. All these gaps are filled by the Borana informal justice system. 42 HARAMAYA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 6:2017] towards his clan and fellow Borana will lose his benefits and privileges. Among the Borana, the combined use of exclusion (abaarsa) and principle of collective responsibility has made the Borana law-abiding. This approach has been shaped by the people’s collectivist and relationship- focused worldview. Collective responsibility is one of the core values embedded in Borana worldview along with mutual survival and interdependence. Among the Borana, crime is viewed as an act which disrupts nagaa Boorana. For the Borana, nagaa (peace) is indivisible and considered as a collective treasure which belongs to all Borana. The philosophy is that to restore nagaa Boorana which is collective, collective response is necessary. In other words, the maintenance of harmonious relations is a shared duty of every Borana. Collective responsibility and sense of shared destiny are necessary features of Borana way of life. The people have successful record in organizing collective action and managing conflict. In general, so far, in terms of performance, the clan-based Borana justice system in general and its principle of collective responsibility seem to have worked well in disciplining its members. Every clan member has been kept within the bounds of the norms of the society because of the fear of being deprived of his social connection which is a severe kind of punishment. Every clan has more or less ensured that its members continued to be law-abiding in fear of paying gumaa. Hence, in the context of Borana clan-based and pastoral social setting, the principle of collective responsibility would still be relevant. In the context of Ethiopia in general, where there are diverse indigenous justice systems operating, studies have to be made to determine the potential each one may have in preventing crime in the concerned societies. As they are derived from local experiences, indigenous knowledge systems of the people are more suitable in addressing local problems including crimes than the one imposed by the State. The practice of involving the community in the prevention of crime which is working among the Borana can be used by the formal justice system itself. * * * * * work_h2acv4v3zrdpfbyukavcy2wfl4 ---- Microsoft Word - geoforum EJ editorial6final.doc Geographies of Environmental Justice The concept of environmental justice, from its earliest emergence in the civil rights politics of the United States, has always been intensely geographical. The legal and political contestation of proposals to site polluting and toxic facilities in predominantly poor and black communities, which formed the central political mobilisation of the US environmental justice movement, focused on questions of distribution, inequality and injustice which resonate with long standing traditions of geographical enquiry and analysis. The body of US based literature on environmental justice contains substantial contributions by geographers, including multiple empirical studies of patterns of location of industrial and waste sites, historical research on processes of co-evolution of urban and industrial development, and analysis of environmental justice activism in general and in particular settings. Not surprisingly much of this work has been framed by the particularities of environmental justice in the US. Whilst there are significant exceptions, attention has predominantly been given to the socio-spatial distribution of pollution and ‘toxicity’ within US national borders, to the politics of race and civil rights, and to policy responses to accusations of environmental racism in facility siting. However, the terminology of environmental justice has now travelled beyond the US and the sites of grassroots activism within which it originated. Whilst retaining its potency in relation to grassroots and everyday struggles against injustice at multiple political sites (Dunion and Scandrett 2003; Schlosberg 2004), this ‘fast conceptual transfer’ (Debbane and Keil 2004: 209) has taken place mainly within political and academic elites. Principles of environmental justice have as a consequence begun to feature within policy rhetoric and the work of mainstream institutions operating in varied places and at different scales of governance. For example, in the UK environmental justice (or, frequently ‘environmental inequality’ or ‘environment and social justice’, the terminological significance of which may serve do particular political work in terms of what is included in the politics of justice and the environment) has been included in the strategic priorities of the main environmental regulatory agency, the Environment Agency (Chalmers and Colvin 2005), and features repeatedly within the new national strategy for sustainable development, Securing the Future (DEFRA 2005). In South Africa, principles of environmental CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by Lancaster E-Prints https://core.ac.uk/display/71733?utm_source=pdf&utm_medium=banner&utm_campaign=pdf-decoration-v1 justice have been bought into the mainstream through their inclusion in the Constitution (Patel, this volume), and within the negotiations and documentation of multilateral environmental agreements, principles of equity and justice frequently surface (Okereke, this volume). In breaking away from its origins and initial framing in the US, the concept of environmental justice is evolving to become broader in scope and more encompassing in the sites, forms and processes of injustice it is concerned with. In becoming more globalised, the environmental justice agenda is extending into questions of distribution both between and across nation-states (Stephens et al 2001; Newell 2005), and into very different political, cultural and economic environments (Ageyman et al, 2003). Justice ‘to whom’ is being cast in more inclusive terms to include, for example, differences of gender, age and the rights of future generations (Buckingham- Hatfield et al 2005; Dobson 1998). Notions of the environment have similarly broadened to include access to environmental goods and resources such as water, energy and greenspace (Lucas et al 2004, Heynen 2003) and the threat of ‘natural’ as well as technologically produced risks, interfacing here with ‘vulnerability’ literatures (Walker et al 2006; Adger et al. 2003; Pelling 2005) Whilst opening up new pathways for activism, academic analysis, and institutional intervention, a dynamic and expansive environmental justice agenda also raises many challenges. This special issue of Geoforum considers such challenges and their implications by explicitly focusing on arenas within which environmental justice has to date been relatively unexplored. First presented at a session on environmental justice organised by the Planning and Environment Research Group of the Royal Geographical Society/Institute of British Geographers at the International Geographical Congress, held in Glasgow in August 2004 1 , the papers demonstrate the resurgence of critical concern with issues of environmental justice, and broader issues of (in)justice and (in)equality, within the geographical imagination. In exploring the varied geographies of environmental justice, the papers take on board the need to examine the evolution and application of the concept outside of the narrow confines of the US, and beyond western liberal notions of environment and justice. To this end, 1 Other papers from the conference session concerned specifically with the UK context have been published in Local Environment: the International Journal for Justice and Sustainability, 10 (4). each of the papers is seeking a critical engagement with the use of an environmental justice framework. They do so in different post-colonial political and cultural contexts - India, Ireland, South Africa, Australia, Singapore - and at different scales of articulation extending from the particular local case, through to institutions of international environmental governance. In setting the scene for these discussions, in the remainder of this editorial we consider three particular challenges for the development of (geographical) research on environmental justice: first, how questions of terminology, meaning and definition may be addressed; second, the connections between environmental justice and sustainability; and finally, how notions of environmental justice must confront issues of multiplicity and diversity. Environmental justice and inequality Despite the long history of theoretical discussion over the term justice and all that it implies, the notion of environmental justice, in part reflecting its roots in a social movement, has been subject to less intensive interrogation and definitional precision. The way in which the notion of environmental justice has been deployed has been more as an instinctive gut reaction than as a closely argued concept. There are, of course, some extensive and rigorous treatments (e.g. Dobson 1998; Low and Gleeson 1998), but in the main the impulse has been to call for environmental justice as a response to perceived injustice, as judged through observations of unreasonable inequality in outcome and lack of ‘fair treatment’ for, in particular, people and social groups that are already marginalised and disadvantaged. Given that there are some shared, common sense understandings of environmental injustice/justice, further conceptual deliberation and clarification may not be all that useful. On the other hand, as the concept breaks free from its initial moorings and is at once translated into other political sites of intervention and taken up within mainstream political institutions, exploring critically its varied meanings and keeping hold of a (radical) sense of justice may be important. Several of the papers in this issue take some time to consider the meaning of justice in an environmental context, demonstrating the complexities and diversity of perspectives that can be adopted and recruited for strategic purposes. It we take the idea of environmental justice as equality the “familiar and crucial practical question … equality of what is raised. Should it be opportunities (after liberal convention), primary goods (after Rawls), resources (after Dworkin), capabilities (after Sen) or welfare outcomes?” (Smith 2000: 6). In the main, much of the attention initially given to environmental justice adopted a consequential focus on (in)equality of outcomes, that is of the distribution of environmental risks (Schlosberg 2004). There are, however, concerns about a language of justice based on the premise of distributional equality. First, in relation to environmental risks, this logically could be addressed by the even sharing of environmental burdens rather than by addressing any of the route causes of environmental problems (Dobson, 1998). Second, given that much of the environment, when broadly defined, is inherently and sometimes uniquely distributed into particular places and cannot sensibly be experienced equally or uniformly, it can become positively perverse to be seeking its ‘even’ distribution (whatever that might mean). In this sense, an unequal distribution of environmental goods or bads by itself may not necessarily be unjust (Walker et al 2005a) – it is rather the ‘fairness’ of the processes through which the distribution has occurred and the possibilities which individuals and communities have to avoid or ameliorate risk, or to access environmental resources, which are important. In part for these reasons, both within movements for environmental justice and in academic discourse, alternative notions of justice have been deployed, in terms of both ‘recognition’ (Schlosberg 2004) and participation in the processes through which decisions about exposure to risks and access to resources take place. There is much to be debated here, but, we would argue, no necessity to pursue an agenda of absolute definitional precision and commonality of perspective. Whilst Ikeme (2003; 195) appeals for conceptual clarity and a ‘unifying framework’, the ethical and ideological character of justice theory can only serve to maintain plurality and alternative perspectives are likely to be more or less appropriate to different practical and analytical contexts (there are further tensions here between universal notions of justice/rights and justice worked out on the ground in particular places; see below). Furthermore, the term ‘equity’, rather unhelpfully, too easily slips in its use between the descriptive sense of inequality, and the normative sense of justice, providing a further complication for the search for clarity in language and meaning. The papers in this volume ably demonstrate the need to conceive environmental justice as a ‘broad church’ within which different notions of justice are encompassed. Williams and Mawdsly and Davies emphasise process dimensions, considering the ways in which groups are able to articulate and practise environmental justice activism and take forward agendas, which in turn raise questions of distribution, access and recognition. Hobson, argues that a performative approach can provide an alternative way of viewing environmental justice and its role in everyday political struggles. Patel and Okereke both focus on institutions and the ways in which the egalitarian notions of justice in sustainable development are worked out in practice and constrained in turn by technocratic approaches and a neoliberal emphasis on market efficiency. Hillman suggests that alongside any treatment of the distributional and procedural aspects of environmental justice, due consideration must also be given to ecological justice – in the form of relationships between the social and natural worlds (Low and Gleeson 1998) – and to the ways in which the ‘environment’ is defined in particular social and historical contexts. Not only are multiple dimensions of environment and justice invoked across the papers, but their persistent entanglement suggests that outside the realms of abstract conceptual debate, separating out the multiple dimensions of justice and environment may both be futile and of only limited value. Environmental justice and sustainability In making a journey from its initial conceptualisation, environmental justice has more directly entered the intellectual and policy territory of sustainable development raising questions of interrelationship and relative utility (Ageyman and Evans 2004). Given that sustainable development provides the meta-narrative for environmental concerns it is necessary to ask if the environmental justice vocabulary and analytical lens adds anything useful to what is already in place. Is this just a new unhelpful, branding which begins to take apart the integrative discourse and values of sustainable development? Two key issues are illuminating here. First, whether concepts of justice and equity are reconcilable between the two sets of discourses. 2 Second, how notions of environmental justice seek to engage with the traditional model of sustainable development as a means through which to engage economic, social and environmental concerns simultaneously. If we look back to the Brundtland Report (WCED 1987) as the primary source of conceptualisation of sustainable development, notions of equity and justice are fundamental. The focus on meeting the needs of current and future generations both centres on current inequalities in the meeting of basic needs and establishes the pursuit of intra and intergenerational equity as key dimensions of future progress towards sustainability. If the ability to live in an environment which meets reasonable standards of quality and tolerable levels of environmental risk is included as a basic need, and one which the Brundtland Report argues is intrinsically necessary for meeting other social needs, then addressing these environmental needs and pursuing environmental justice is manifestly encompassed within, if not central to, the broader framing of sustainable development. In practice, however, from the very earliest stages of implementation, translation and re-presentation of the notion of sustainable development, there have been criticisms that equity and justice issues have been downplayed. Nowhere is this perhaps more apparent than in the continuing tensions over responsibilities and equitable approaches to addressing international environmental problems, such as climate change (Okereke, this volume). ‘Weak’ forms of sustainability have been criticised as casting environmental protection in economic terms, whilst ‘strong’ forms of sustainability have been seen to neglect the impacts that moves to sustain critical environmental capital might have on social equity. In this way, the environmental and social dimensions of sustainability have tended to be separately pursued, neglecting their interactions and attendant equity and justice implications (Patel, this volume). When set alongside the failure of environmental movements to engage with how environmental quality is being experienced by marginalised communities at a ‘doorstep’ level; the possibility that the new participatory and deliberative agenda of environmental decision-making may be serving to exclude some ‘public’ voices 2 Within the sustainable development discourse the term equity is typically used rather than justice but, as noted above, without a clear definitional distinction whilst privileging others; and the failure of policy appraisal and impact assessment tools to consider how environmental change may be socially distributed (Walker et al 2005b), it is hard to argue that all of the many concerns that there might be about how the environment is regressively socially distributed, the fairness of decision-making procedures and the negative social consequences of environmental policy, have been adequately given voice, researched and addressed within the 20-year discourse of sustainable development. Nonetheless, it would be a mistake to view environmental justice as simply plugging this gap. While the discourses and mobilisations of environmental justice provide the political space to consider the ‘socio-environmental’ aspects of sustainability, including, for example, issues of fuel poverty, graffiti and vandalism in the UK (Lucas et al 2004), or the differentials of water use and water culture in South Africa (Debbane and Keil 2004: 222), the agenda is both more far-reaching and more fundamental. Rather than being only concerned with the surface manifestations of environmental injustice, as a political programme environmental justice is concerned with the underlying causes and dynamics of inequities at different scales. Thus, in the context of the urban, for example, ‘there is no such thing as an unsustainable city in general. Rather, there are a series of urban and environmental processes that negatively effect some social groups while benefiting others’ (Swyngedouw and Heynen 2003:901). In seeking to understand the causes and consequences of environmental inequities, and the ways in which they can be addressed, we necessarily confront the relations between the economy, society and the state (Newell 2005). Rather than providing a further prop to existing notions of sustainable development, in these ways, environmental justice may bring enable new critical engagements with the relations between economy, environment and society, and illuminate the radical potential of sustainability. As Debbane and Keil (2004:222) argue ‘we must remind ourselves of the perhaps most important single aspect of the global, multiscale environmental justice movement in its various incarnations: its function to provide a safeguard against the depoliticisation of environmental politics.’ In this light, we would argue that the addition of environmental justice as ‘a vocabulary of political opportunity’ (Agyeman and Evans, 2004), and a new framing for research and policy attention in which equity is brought to the foreground, is both welcome and necessary. However, it is critical to ensure that as notions of environmental justice enter into mainstream discourses, the elasticity of the concept does not mean that it is reduced to the (relatively) comfortable assessment of how local, visible manifestations of social justice problems can be ‘cleaned up’ and how environmental law can be more strictly enforced (both of which have been evident in governmental interpretations in the UK). Rather, in refocusing attention on equity and inequity within sustainable development, environmental justice has the potential to provide a productive intellectual and policy space for multidimensional and multi- scalar exploration of its many meanings, manifestations and implications. Environmental justice, multiplicity and diversity Recognition of the plurality of the meanings and principles of environmental justice poses a further challenge to those who seek to identify a set of universal principles of justice and sustainability. For some, ‘notions of justice and notions of movements linked to justice struggles are highly diverse and can not be measured or expressed in universal terms’ (Debbane and Keil 2004: 209). For others, the acceptance of different concepts of justice leads to the kind of relativism which makes any notion of justice in the first instance meaningless (Low and Gleeson 1998). Schlosberg (2004) suggests that an alternative is possible. In recognising the importance of context in shaping struggles for environmental justice, it is argued that by confronting the underlying logics of inequity through multiple sites, a unified, if not uniform, environmental justice movement can be forged (Schlosberg 2004: 534). The papers in this volume, by taking seriously the difference that different contexts make in shaping discourses and practices of environmental inequities, provide insights into the tensions between universal and particular notions of environmental justice, while Willams and Mawdsley (this volume) explicitly consider the validity of Scholsberg’s arguments for engaging with environmental justice in a post-colonial context. At the same time, engaging with environmental justice poses significant material challenges for those seeking equity in access to resources and in protection from harm. Where the ‘environment of justice’ – be it access to clean air, to water, productive land and so on – is subject to change, assessing what constitutes just access and just protection carries additional conceptual and practical challenges (Hillman, this volume). Given that arguments for environmental justice extend across spatial and temporal scales, and the complexities of the environmental systems within which justice is sought, uncertainties about future environmental goods and bads provide another critical issue with which concepts and policies of environmental justice have to engage (Hillman, this volume, Okereke, this volume). There are also local contingencies in the conditions under which environmental justice arguments are and can be evoked within strategies of resistance and activism. Davies (this volume) contrasts the lack of environmental justice discourse in the case of protests against the siting of an incinerator in Ireland, with the political opportunities this could provide in the future through the deployment of scaling-up opportunities, linking with other social justice movements and exploiting the rights now enshrined within the Aarhus convention. In the context of the distinctive capitalist state of Singapore, Hobson (this volume) argues that environmental justice is implicit and performative in the enactment of environmental care and in micro- struggles over the meanings and uses of space, despite the absence of liberal democratic institutions and formal opportunities for political activism. In India Williams and Mawdsley (this volume) emphasise various ways in which the postcolonial experience shapes and constrains opportunities for pursuing a western model of environmental justice. They argue that the western model becomes particularly problematic in its faith in a deliberative democracy that will be inclusive and afford recognition to all and in the expectation that state action to manage the environment will be both effective and applied in non-discriminatory ways. They more generally conclude from their analysis that “regardless of the theoretical lens through which concepts of injustice are viewed … a close examination of differences in the context in which struggles for environmental justice are located is required” This conclusion pervades each of the papers in this volume and provides an important intervention in the sometimes too easy movement of ideas, approaches and concepts between places and contexts. It is also a timely reminder of the need to consider geography in all of its dimensions in the deployment of an environmental justice discourse and frame of analysis. References Adger, N., Huq, S., ,Brown, K., Conway, D. and Hulme, M. (2003) Adaptation to climate change in the developing world, Progress in Development Studies, 3 (3): 179- 195 Agyeman, J., Bullard, R. D. and Evans, B. (2003) Just Sustainabilities: development in an unequal world, Earthscan, London Agyeman, J. & Evans, B. (2004) Just sustainability: the emerging discourse of environmental justice in Britain?, The Geographical Journal, 170(2), pp. 155–164. Buckingham-Hatfield, S., Reeves, D. and Batchelor, A. (2005) Wasting women: the environmental justice of including women in municipal waste management, Local Environment, 10(4), pp 427-444 Chalmers, H. and Colvin, J. (2005) Addressing Environmental Inequalities in UK Policy: an action research perspective, Local Environment, 10(4), pp. 333-360. DEFRA (2005) Securing the Future: Delivering the UK Sustainable Development Strategy, London: The Stationary Office Dobson, A. (1998) Justice and the environment: conceptions of environmental sustainability and dimensions of social justice, Oxford University Press, Oxford Dunion, K. and Scandrett, E. (2003) The campaign for environmental justice in Scotland as a response to poverty in a northern nation, in J Agyeman , R Bullard and B Evans (eds) Just Sustainabilities: development in an unequal world, Earthscan, London Debbané, A. and Keil, R. (2004) Multiple disconnections: environmental justice and urban water in Canada and South Africa, Space and Polity , 8 (2): 209-225. Heynen N. C. (2003) The Scalar Production of Injustice within the Urban Forest, Antipode, 35 (5) 980-998 Ikeme, J. (2003) Equity, environmental justice and sustainability: incomplete approaches to climate change politics, Global Environmental Change 13: 195-206 Low, N. and Gleeson, B. (1998) Justice, society and nature: an exploration of political ecology, Routledge. London Lucas, K., Walker, G., Eames, M., Fay, H., and Poustie, M. (2004) Environment and Social Justice: Rapid Research and Evidence Review, Sustainable Development Research Network, Policy Studies Institute, London. Newell, P. (2005) Race, class and the global politics of environmental inequality, Global Environmental Politics, 5 (3): 70-94 Pelling, M. (2005) The Vulnerability of Cities: natural disasters and social resilience, Earthscan, London. Scholsberg, D. (2004) Reconceiving environmental justice: global movements and political theories, Environmental Politics, 13 (3): 517-540. Smith, D. (2000) Moral progress in human geography: transcending the place of good fortune, Progress in Human Geography, 24 (1): 1-18. Stephens, C., Bullock, S. and Scott, A. (2001) Environmental Justice: rights and mean to a healthy environment for all, Special Briefing Paper 7, ESRC Global Environmental Change Programme Swyngedouw, E. and Heynen, N. (2003) Urban political ecology, justice and the politics of scale, Antipode 35 (5), 898-918 Walker, G. P., Mitchell, G., Fairburn, J. and Smith, G. (2005a) Industrial pollution and social deprivation: evidence and complexity in evaluating and responding to environmental inequality, Local Environment, 10(4), pp 361-377 Walker, G. P., Fay, H. and Mitchell, G. (2005b) Environmental Justice Impact Assessment: an evaluation of requirements and tools for distributional analysis, a report for Friends of the Earth England and Wales, FoE, London. Walker, G., Burningham, K., Fielding, J. and Smith, G. (2006) Addressing Environmental Inequalities: Flood Risk, Environment Agency, Bristol. WCED (World Commission on Environment and Development) (1987) Our Common Future, Oxford University Press, Oxford. work_h4k7s5vehzfjfagzr3naobpqfm ---- Rangelov Iavor Justice as a security strategy? International justice and the liberal peace in the Balkans Article (Accepted version) (Refereed) Original citation: Rangelov, Iavor (2016) Justice as a security strategy? International justice and the liberal peace in the Balkans. Journal of Conflict and Security Law, 21 (1). pp. 9-28. ISSN 1467-7954 DOI: 10.1093/jcsl/krv017 © 2015 Oxford University Press This version available at: http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/66914/ Available in LSE Research Online: June 2016 LSE has developed LSE Research Online so that users may access research output of the School. Copyright © and Moral Rights for the papers on this site are retained by the individual authors and/or other copyright owners. Users may download and/or print one copy of any article(s) in LSE Research Online to facilitate their private study or for non-commercial research. You may not engage in further distribution of the material or use it for any profit-making activities or any commercial gain. You may freely distribute the URL (http://eprints.lse.ac.uk) of the LSE Research Online website. This document is the author’s final accepted version of the journal article. There may be differences between this version and the published version. You are advised to consult the publisher’s version if you wish to cite from it. http://www.lse.ac.uk/internationalDevelopment/people/rangelovi.aspx http://jcsl.oxfordjournals.org/ http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/jcsl/krv017 http://global.oup.com/?cc=gb http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/66914/ 1 Justice as a Security Strategy? International Justice and the Liberal Peace in the Balkans Iavor Rangelov 1 Abstract The establishment of the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia (ICTY) in the midst of the war in Bosnia and Herzegovina was seen by many as a radical innovation in security thinking and practice. This paper examines the security implications of international justice in the Balkans by situating the analysis within the broader context of international interventions in the region. The paper starts by elaborating a distinctive conception of ‘security’ that emerges from the pursuit of international justice, addressing questions such as security for whom, security from what, and security by what means. It then examines the jurisprudence of the ICTY to determine whether judicial practice has tended to promote this distinctive approach to security. The final section explores the interactions of international justice and liberal peace interventions in the Balkans, focusing in particular on peacemaking, peacekeeping and peacebuilding. The paper argues that the revival of international justice half a century after the Nuremberg Trials can be understood as signaling a shift in security paradigms from statism to human rights, while also giving rise to deep tensions between them. These tensions are most clearly expressed in the interactions of international justice with other security instruments of the liberal peace, which are often employed by the international community in situations where international crimes occur. 1 Global Security Research Fellow, Department of International Development, London School of Economics and Political Science; Co-Chair, London Transitional Justice Network. E-mail: i.p.rangelov@lse.ac.uk. I would like to thank the participants at the conference ‘Law, Justice, and the Security Gap’, held in June 2014 at LSE, for comments on an earlier draft of this paper, and the European Research Council for financial support. 2 1. Introduction The establishment of the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia (ICTY) in the midst of the war in Bosnia and Herzegovina was hailed by some as a development that marked the beginning of the end of impunity for egregious human rights violations, ushering in an era in which global security policy would be underpinned by concern for the security of individuals and communities and not only the security of States. Others were much more sceptical, however, arguing that the international community of States, acting through the UN Security Council and its Chapter VII powers to maintain international peace and security, was setting up courts to prosecute atrocities it could have prevented from occurring in the first place, staging trials instead of putting their soldiers’ lives on the line to protect civilians. Neither side was wrong. The deliberations at the Security Council that led to the creation of the Tribunal were dominated by statements expressing concern for the plight of civilians in the Balkans and enthusiasm for a revival of the Nuremberg legacy that could pave the way for a permanent international criminal court. 2 In less than a decade, the International Criminal Court had been established and questions of accountability and justice for serous international crimes were featuring regularly in global security discussions. Shortly after it had decided to put in place a tribunal for the former Yugoslavia, the Security Council was preoccupied with the unfolding genocide in Rwanda. A twin court, the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda (ICTR), was set up in the wake of the most dramatic failure of the international community since the end of the Cold War to prevent and stop mass slaughter: “Law became a euphemism for inaction.” 3 These early debates are still relevant because they highlight the need to analyse the role of international justice in the security arena at two levels: with respect to the evolving normative underpinnings of security concepts and practices and, at the same time, in relation to other security instruments that are employed (or not) by the international community alongside international justice. Understanding the distinctive logic of international justice as a security instrument is important but insufficient on its own; it has to be complemented by an examination of the interactions of international justice with other security instruments that are simultaneously deployed and brought to bear in a particular context, especially when such instruments may constrain or reinforce the pursuit of justice in significant ways. 2 See Record of the 3175 th Meeting of the UNSC, 22 February 1993, UN Doc. S/PV.3175 (1993). 3 GJ Bass, Stay the Hand of Vengeance: The Politics of War Crimes Tribunals (Princeton University Press 2000) 215. 3 This article examines the security implications of international justice in the Balkans by situating the analysis within the broader context of international interventions in the region. It argues that the revival of international justice half a century after the Nuremberg and Tokyo trials could be interpreted as signaling a shift in security paradigms from statism to human rights while also giving rise to deep tensions between them. These tensions are most clearly expressed in the interactions of international justice with a set of security instruments associated with the ‘liberal peace’, which in one form or another have been routinely employed in situations where serious international crimes occur since the 1990s. 4 The argument is elaborated in relation to the Balkans, a region that has served as a laboratory for the international community in developing both transitional justice and liberal peace approaches to conflict-affected states. The concurrent evolution of these approaches over the past two decades has reinforced the idea that transitional justice is central to liberal peacebuilding and claims to that effect have become commonplace among practitioners and scholars. 5 The analysis presented here suggests that such claims should be treated with caution, however, and calls for a critical re-consideration of the relationship between transitional justice and the liberal peace. It also raises questions about a core set of critiques of the liberal peace that identify as the main problem the ‘liberalism’ of the interveners: “If only they were not, in various ways, so liberal, then it is alleged external intervention or assistance may potentially be much less problematic.” 6 The contribution reflects the overall preoccupation of the special issue with ‘security cultures’ as an analytical lens for investigating the role of law and justice in global security. A security culture combines a set of ideas and a set of practices that tend to reinforce each other. As Kaldor points out, a security culture is not a static concept; it is constructed and has to be continuously reproduced: “Understanding the mechanisms through which cultures are constructed enables us to identify openings and closures – points at which policy innovations are possible and where they are stuck… The aim is to substantiate specific security cultures 4 The article focuses on security instruments at the sharp end of the ‘liberal peace’, which refers to a broader set of interventions in fragile and conflict-affected states based on the idea that peace depends on the existence of liberal political and economic institutions that are functioning and effective, and aimed at constructing liberal polities, economies, and societies. See, e.g, A Bellamy, ‘The “Next Stage” in Peace Operations Theory’, in A Bellamy and P Williams (eds) Peace Operations and Global Order (Routledge 2007); M Duffield, Global Governance and the New Wars: The Merging of Development and Security (Zed Books 2001); R Paris, At War’s End: Building Peace after Civil Conflict (CUP 2002); O Richmond, ‘The Problem of Peace: Understanding the “Liberal Peace”’ (2006) 6(3) Conflict, Security & Development 291-314. 5 See Rule of Law and Transitional Justice in Conflict and Post-conflict Societies, Report of the Secretary General, UN Doc. S/2004/616 (223 August 2004). See generally CL Sriram, ‘Justice as Peace? Liberal Peacebuilding and Strategies of Transitional Justice’ (2007) 21(4) Global Society 579-591. 6 D Chandler, ‘The Uncritical Critique of ‘Liberal Peace’’ (2010) 36 Rev of Int’l Studies 137-155, 144. 4 and the ways in which they are constructed so as to understand and interpret their different internal logics.” 7 This approach is productive for examining international justice and the liberal peace because it draws attention to the ways in which their relationship is mediated by certain sets of ideas and practices that reflect particular logics and these logics, in turn, structure their interactions. Peace usually refers to peace between states, whereas human rights tend to be about the domestic arena. The liberal peace is statist in that the priority is peace between collective actors (the warring parties) rather than human rights, which are at the heart of the project of international justice. As a security culture, the liberal peace involves a combination of statist objectives and statist methods of enforcement that contradicts the logic of a human rights approach and complicates its pursuit in practice. The article proceeds in three sections. The first section traces the evolution of international justice from its origins in the wake of World War II to its revival half a century later with the establishment of the Yugoslav Tribunal. The aim is to elaborate a distinctive conception of ‘security’ that emerges from this trajectory, addressing questions such as security for whom, security from what, and security by what means. The following section examines the jurisprudence of the ICTY to determine whether judicial practice has tended to promote this distinctive approach to security. The final section explores the interactions of international justice and liberal peace interventions in the Balkans, focusing in particular on three types of security instruments that have been deployed in the region in conjunction with international justice: peacemaking, peacekeeping and peacebuilding. 2. Reinventing Justice, Reframing Security The foundations of international criminal justice were laid down by the Allies in the wake of World War II with the establishment of the International Military Tribunal at Nuremberg (Nuremberg Tribunal) and the International Military Tribunal for the Far East in Tokyo (Tokyo Tribunal) for the prosecution of major war criminals of the defeated Axis powers. 8 International justice had been suspended for nearly five decades when the Security Council 7 M Kaldor, ‘Security Cultures’, Security in Transition Working Paper, July 2015, 9. 8 Charter of the International Military Tribunal, annexed to the Agreement for the Prosecution and Punishment of the Major War Criminals of the European Axis, 8 August 1945, 59 Stat. 1544, 82 UNTS 279 (1945) (hereinafter Nuremberg Charter); Charter of the International Military Tribunal for the Far East, reproduced in International Military Tribunal of the Far East, Established in Tokyo, Jan. 19, 1946, US Department of State Pub. No. 2675 (1946) (hereinafter Tokyo Charter). 5 unanimously decided to establish the ICTY in February 1993. 9 The decision was seen as advancing the principles and legacy of the Nuremberg trials. There were, however, fundamental differences between the birth of international justice and its resurrection half a century later. With respect to the main purpose and justification of conducting criminal prosecutions at the international level, the Nuremberg Tribunal was set up to punish violations of state sovereignty committed in the context of a ‘total war’, whereas the Yugoslav Tribunal was created to prosecute human rights violations inflicted in pursuit of ‘ethnic cleansing’. The different rationales are reflected in the character of the central offense and have shaped the exercise of international justice at these junctures in other important ways, harnessing international law and forum to promote shifting paradigms of security. An early version of the rationale behind the Nuremberg trials was set out in a report of the Czechoslovak delegate to the United Nations War Crimes Commission (UNWCC, a body created to investigate crimes and identify suspects) in March 1944, which made the case for the offenses subsequently codified in the Nuremberg Charter as ‘crimes against peace’: His thesis was that the paramount crime was the launching and waging of the Second World War, and that individuals responsible for it should be held penally liable and tried accordingly. The criminal nature of the last war was found to derive from its aim and methods. The aims were to enslave foreign nations, to destroy their civilization and physically annihilate a considerable section of their population on racial, political or religious grounds. The methods arouse from the fact that it was a “total” war, which disregarded all humanitarian considerations lying at the root of the laws and customs of war, and introduced indiscriminate means of warfare and barbaric methods of occupation. 10 The central offense selected for prosecution and punishment was the violation of state sovereignty pursued by means of military conquest and occupation. Crimes against peace were prosecuted as the paramount crime at Nuremberg, defined as “planning, preparation, initiation or waging of war of aggression, or a war in violation of international treaties, agreements and assurances, or participation in a common plan and conspiracy for the 9 SC Res 808, UN Doc S/RES/808 (1993); SC Res 827, UN Doc S/Res/827 (1993) adopted the Statute of the International Tribunal as annexed to the Report of the Secretary General pursuant to paragraph 2 of SC Res 808, UN Doc S/25704 (1993) (hereinafter ICTY Statute). 10 UNWCC, History of the United Nations War Crimes Commission and the Development of the Law of War (H.M.S.O. 1948), 180. 6 accomplishment of any of the foregoing.” 11 War crimes and crimes against humanity were also prosecuted at Nuremberg but these offenses were seen as secondary because they emanated, as it were, from the cardinal crime of planning and waging aggressive war. The hierarchy of crimes was made explicit in the Charter of the Tokyo Tribunal, where crimes against humanity and war crimes on their own were not sufficient for assuming jurisdiction: “The Tribunal shall have the power to try and punish Far Eastern war criminal who as individuals or members of organizations are charged with offenses that include Crimes against Peace.” 12 The Nuremberg Judgment reaffirmed the superior status of crimes against peace in relation to other international crimes: The charges in the Indictment that the defendants planned and waged aggressive wars are charges of the utmost gravity. War is essentially an evil thing. Its consequences are not confined to the belligerent States but affect the whole world. To initiate a war of aggression, therefore, is not only an international crime; it is the supreme international crime differing only from other war crimes in that it contains within itself the accumulated evil of the whole. 13 Nuremberg’s obsession with aggression has been the subject of much criticism. One problem was the way it affected the framing of crimes against humanity, the other major innovation of the trials, by establishing a nexus to international armed conflict. Crimes against humanity could be prosecuted only in connection with either crimes against peace or war crimes, even though this charge was supposed to capture the crimes of the Holocaust. Hannah Arendt observed that what had prevented the judges from doing full justice to crimes against humanity was that the Nuremberg Charter “demanded that this crime, which had so little to do with war that its commission actually conflicted with and hindered the war’s conduct, was to be bound up with the other crimes.” 14 Others have argued that the Nuremberg legacy was compromised by limiting the enforcement of human rights to atrocities committed in the course of pursuing aggressive war by the defeated party, raising the problem of ‘victors’ justice’. David Luban observers that the aspirations of the Nuremberg trials to vindicate the rights of human beings were called into question by the 11 Nuremberg Charter, Article 6. 12 Tokyo Charter, Article 5. 13 International Military Tribunal (Nuremberg). Judgment and Sentences, 1 October 1946, reproduced in 41(1) AJIL 172-333 (1947), 186. 14 H Arendt, Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil (Penguin 1994), 258. 7 failure to prosecute crimes committed in Germany before the war as well as those committed by Allied war criminals. 15 Against the background of Nuremberg, the creation of the Yugoslav Tribunal could be interpreted not simply as a revival but a reinvention of international criminal justice, signalling a paradigm shift. The main concern of the international community was the growing evidence of mass atrocities in the former Yugoslavia. By late 1992, the Security Council had put in place a commission to investigate violations of international humanitarian law committed in the region. 16 The Commission of Experts reported that mass killings, rape, torture and destruction of civilian, cultural and religious property had been committed in the context of ethnic cleansing, and suggested that an international criminal tribunal was established to investigate and prosecute the ongoing violations. 17 Acting under Chapter VII powers of the UN Charter to maintain international peace and security, the Security Council established the ICTY with a mandate to bring to justice those responsible for serious violations of international humanitarian law committed on the territory of the former Yugoslavia since 1991. 18 The primacy of human rights in the new paradigm is evident from what was included in the substantive jurisdiction of the Tribunal – war crimes (grave breaches of the Geneva Conventions of 1949 and violations of the laws and customs of war), crimes against humanity, and genocide – and what was missing: crimes against peace. Prosecution and punishment at the international level was justified in relation to supressing human rights violations rather than violations of state sovereignty. Despite the fact that the Security Council acted under Chapter VII and the disintegration of Yugoslavia had sparked heated debates over sovereignty, international justice was not concerned with aggression – the classic threat to international peace and security as these are traditionally understood. It was invoked as a response to ethnic cleansing targeting the civilian population. In line with this approach, the definition of crimes against humanity was expanded to incorporate offenses such as rape and torture. 19 The Security Council established the ICTY in the midst of the war in Bosnia and Herzegovina on the understanding that bringing perpetrators of international crimes to justice 15 D Luban, Legal Modernism (University of Michigan Press 1994). 16 SC Res 870, UN Doc S/RES/870 (1992). 17 See Interim Report of the Commission of Experts, reproduced in Annex I of Letter dated 9 February 1993 from the Secretary General addressed to the President of the Security Council, UN Doc S/25274 (1994). 18 See supra n 8. 19 ICTY Statute, Article 5. 8 would contribute to halting and redressing such violations and this, in turn, would facilitate the restoration and maintenance of peace. 20 This unorthodox approach was animated by a particular logic, reflecting the idea that the prospect for peace in the former Yugoslavia depended on suppressing extreme nationalism and criminalizing its goals and methods: ethnic cleansing and genocide. 21 International justice was viewed as a particularly suitable instrument in that respect because it focused on perpetrators and victims as individuals, effectively countering the narratives of collective guilt and victimhood that were prevalent in the region and fuelling the conflict. Madeline Albright, who spearheaded the efforts to establish the Yugoslav and Rwanda Tribunals while serving as US Ambassador to the UN, put it this way at the time: [T]he tribunal will make it easier for the Bosnian people to reach a genuine peace. The scars left on the bodies and in the minds of the survivors of this war will take time to heal. In too many places, neighbours were betrayed by neighbour and friend divided by friend by fierce and hostile passion. Too many families have assembled at too many cemeteries for us to say that ethnic differences in Bosnia do not matter. But responsibility for these crimes does not rest with Serbs or Croats or Muslims as peoples; it rests with the people who ordered and committed the crimes. The wounds opened by this war will heal much faster if collective guilt is expunged and individual responsibility is assigned. 22 This particular framing of the Tribunal’s contribution to peace in the Balkans by individualising guilt for atrocity crimes was subsequently embraced by the judges and prosecutors as well; in fact, they have gone to great lengths to dispel any suspicion that that the Tribunal might be meting out collective guilt and punishment. Former Chief Prosecutor Carla Del Ponte emphasized that point in her opening speech at the trial of Slobodan Milošević: “No state or organisation is on trial here today. The indictments do not accuse an entire people of being collectively guilty of the crimes, not even the crimes of genocide.” 23 This is a self-consciously liberal conception of justice, centred on individuals as bearers of rights and responsibility for violations, and its contribution to peace. 20 SC Res 827. 21 I Rangelov, Nationalism and the Rule of Law: Lessons from the Balkans and Beyond (CUP 2014), 86-90. 22 MK Albright, Address at the US Holocaust Memorial Museum, Washington, DC, 12 April 1994, available at http://www.silent-edge.org/mt/rwanda/albright.html (accessed 20 May 2015). 23 Prosecutor v. Milošević, IT-01-51-I, Transcripts, 12 February 2002, 4. 9 In sum, the evolution of international justice from its origins at the Nuremberg trials to its reinvention half a century later with the establishment of the Yugoslav Tribunal could be interpreted as a shift in security paradigms from statism to human rights. A distinctive conception of ‘security’ can be detected in the pursuit of international justice in the former Yugoslavia by addressing three questions. First, security for whom? Breaking with the state- centricity of the Nuremberg paradigm, in the new paradigm of international justice the referent object of security are individuals rather than states. Second, security from what? The key shift in this respect is from violations of state sovereignty to violations of human rights, in particular atrocities, expulsions and other human rights abuses committed in the context of ethnic cleansing. Finally, security by what means? International justice contributes to security by enforcing the rights of victims to redress under international law and holding perpetrators accountable by assigning individual criminal responsibility, and thereby also serving to supress extreme nationalism and counter narratives of collective guilt. Taken together, these three dimensions effectively recast international justice as a security strategy premised on a liberal understanding of criminal law’s contribution to security. 24 3. Adapting and Developing the Law Although the pursuit of international justice in the Balkans appeared to promise a shift in security thinking and practice, it was also clear from the start that fulfilling that promise even partially was bound to involve grappling with serious challenges and was anything but predetermined. Some of the challenges were beyond the control of the Tribunal, for example arresting and transferring suspects to The Hague, but others were within its powers. This section examines a set of tensions and problems arising in the jurisprudence of the Tribunal and considers the ways in which the judges have sought to respond by adapting and developing international law. Adapting the law to the logic and purposes of the new paradigm has been pursued by the ICTY primarily in two ways: firstly, by addressing some of the statist assumptions of the Nuremberg paradigm and international humanitarian law to better reflect the character of the violence in the former Yugoslavia and, secondly, by extending the normative reach of the law to encompass new subjects and offenses that become important from a human rights perspective. 24 As Alan Norrie has pointed out, “Criminal law is, at heart, a practical application of liberal political philosophy.” A Norrie, Crime, Reason and History: A Critical Introduction to Criminal Law (Weidenfeld & Nicolson 1993) 10. 10 One aspect of the state-centricity of international humanitarian law concerns the classic distinction between ‘international’ armed conflict between states and ‘non- international’ or ‘internal’ armed conflict within states. The emphasis on state borders and sovereignty animates this distinction not only in a descriptive sense but also normatively since the same type of abuses may be proscribed and give rise to individual criminal responsibility when committed in interstate conflicts but not in civil ones – a discrepancy in the laws of war that Steven Ratner has called one of the ‘schizophrenias’ of international criminal law. 25 A lot was at stake for the Tribunal when it secured its first defendant, Duško Tadić, and the proceedings began. The Security Council had abstained from determining the character of the hostilities in the former Yugoslavia when it established the Tribunal, leaving the issue to the judges. There were two problems in applying the distinction to the Yugoslav wars of disintegration. First, the conflict in Bosnia and Herzegovina did not fit easily either the ‘international’ or ‘internal’ category. State borders in the former Yugoslavia were porous, shifting, and hotly contested; if anything, the character of the conflict appeared to be regional and transnational. 26 Second, the distinction was normatively loaded in a way that could not withstand critical scrutiny. Given the gravity of the violations committed in the region, the distinction risked frustrating the humanitarian purposes of the law and appeared unsustainable from a human rights perspective. In dealing with these problems, the ICTY has pursued a twofold approach in its jurisprudence. On the one hand, it has acknowledged that an armed conflict may have both international and non-international elements and has sought to determine under what circumstances an internal conflict may become ‘internationalized’. 27 At the same time, the judges have strived to narrow the gap in protection and have criticised the distinction on principle. In the Tadić Jurisdiction Appeal, the Appeals Chamber highlighted the problems with the distinction as far as human beings were concerned: 25 SR Ratner, ‘The Schizophrenias of International Criminal Law’ (1998) 33(1) Texas Int’l LJ 237-256. 26 On regional conflicts, see generally P Wallenstein and M Sollenberg, ‘Armed Conflict and Regional conflict complexes’ (1997) 35(5) Journal of Peace Research 621-634. 27 The Tadić Appeal Judgement stipulated that an internal conflict “may become international (or, depending upon the circumstances, be international in character) if (i) another State intervenes in that conflict through its troops, or alternatively, (ii) some of the participants in the internal armed conflict act on behalf of that other States”. Prosecutor v. Tadić, T-94-1-A, Judgement, 15 July 1999, para. 84 (hereinafter Tadić Appeal Judgement). For a critique of internationalized armed conflict, which argues for a single law applicable to all armed conflict, see JG Stewart, ‘Towards a Single Definition of Armed Conflict in International humanitarian Law: A Critique of Internationalized Armed Conflict’ (2003) 85 RICR/IRRC 313-349. 11 Why protect civilians from belligerent violence, or ban rape, torture or the wanton destruction of hospitals, churches, museums or private property, as well as proscribe weapons causing unnecessary suffering when two sovereign States are engaged in war, and yet refrain from enacting the same bans or providing the same protection when armed violence has erupted “only” within the territory of a sovereign State? If international law, while of course duly safeguarding the legitimate interests of States, must gradually turn to the protection of human beings, it is only natural that the aforementioned dichotomy should gradually lose its weight. 28 The state-centric view of war that underpinned much of the relevant international law presented other challenges for the Tribunal. What Mary Kaldor calls ‘new wars’ are typically fought by networks of state and non-state actors. 29 In the Yugoslav wars of disintegration, such networks included an array of military and paramilitary forces, regular and irregular police units, militias, criminal groups, private security companies and other actors. One of the legacies of Nuremberg and subsequent domestic trials for the Holocaust in places like France was that crimes against humanity required a nexus to state policy. 30 Dusko Tadic, however, was not a modern-day Eichmann or Goering; he had been running a café and karate courses in Kozarac, a small town in North-Western Bosnia, not armies or ministries. To do justice to crimes against humanity committed in the context of ethnic cleansing in the Balkans, where these offenses appeared to capture both the goals and methods of warfare, the Tribunal had to acknowledge the important role of non-state actors. The Trial Chamber held that “the law in relation to crimes against humanity has developed to take into account forces which, although not those of the legitimate government, have de facto control over, or are able to move freely within, defined territory.” 31 The significance of these developments at the ICTY has been widely acknowledged. William Schabas, for example, argues that as a result of such developments in the law, “perpetrators of serious violations of human rights during non-international armed conflict, including non-State actors, are far less likely to escape justice than they were in the past.” 32 28 Prosecutor v. Tadić, IT-94-I, Decision on the Defence Motion for Interlocutory Appeal on Jurisdiction, 2 October 1995, para. 97 (hereinafter Tadić Jurisdiction Appeal). 29 M Kaldor, New and Old Wars: Organised Violence in a Global Era (Polity 1999). 30 See, for example, Klaus Barbie, Judgement (Chambre criminelle de la Cour de Cassation), 20 December 1985. 31 Prosecutor v. Tadić, IT-94-1-T, Opinion and Judgement, 7 May 1997, para. 654. See also the analysis of the ambiguity created by this interpretation of the law in WA Schabas, ‘Punishment of Non-State Actors in Non- International Armed Conflict’ (2003) 26 Fordham Int’l LJ 907-933, 926-929. 32 Ibid. 922. 12 Much more controversial – and disruptive for the Tribunal itself – has been the effort to adapt the law that relates to modes of criminal liability in ways that could capture the role of state actors in network-based warfare and ethnic cleansing. The complex formal and informal chains of command and the murky relationships forged in the wartime networks in the former Yugoslavia were bound to create problems for the Tribunal. Established theories of liability, such as ‘direct commission’ and ‘command responsibility’, often appeared inadequate when applied to the facts on the ground; at the same time, Nuremberg’s controversial theories of collective criminal liability, such as ‘conspiracy’ and ‘criminal organisation’, were also to be avoided. As a result, a number of cases at the ICTY have involved prosecuting suspects, including Slobodan Milošević, for offenses committed as part of a Joint Criminal Enterprise (JCE) – a doctrine that seemed to offer a viable solution but also aroused much controversy among international lawyers. Initially, the issue with JCE appeared to be that prosecutors and judges at the Tribunal might be using the doctrine as a ‘catch-all’ device, 33 whereas in subsequent cases the judges narrowed its interpretation in ways that were seen by some observers as undermining “JCE’s unique ability to describe criminal arrangements too complex to fit within traditional theories of criminal liability.” 34 JCE divided the Tribunal and sparked public controversy in the case of Gotovina et al., involving three Croatian generals prosecuted for crimes against humanity committed in Operation Storm – the offensive of the Croatian forces in Krajina that effectively ended the war in Croatia. The Trial Chamber unanimously found two of the defendants, Ante Gotovina and Mladen Markač, responsible for participation in a JCE aimed at “the permanent removal of the Serb civilian population from the Krajina by force or threat of force, which amounted to and involved persecution (deportation, unlawful attacks against civilians and civilian objects and discriminatory and restrictive measures), deportation and forcible transfer,” and sentenced them to 24 and 18 years, respectively. 35 A divided Appeals Chamber (three to two), however, reversed the finding of the Trial Chamber that a JCE existed beyond reasonable doubt and acquitted the defendants on that basis. 36 In a strongly worded dissenting opinion, Judge Pocar entertained the possibility that the majority might be driven by ulterior motives in quashing 33 See S Powles, ‘Joint Criminal Enterprise: Criminal Liability by Prosecutorial Ingenuity and Judicial Creativity’ (2004) 2 J of Int’l Criminal Justice 606-619. 34 A O’Rourke, ‘Joint Criminal Enterprise and Brđanin: Misguided Over-Correction’ (2006) 47(1) Harvard Int’l LJ 307-325, 307. 35 Prosecutor v. Gotovina, Markač & Čermak, IT-06-90-T, Judgement, 15 April 2011, paras. 2600, 2617-2618. 36 Prosecutor v. Gotovina & Markač, IT-60-90-A, Judgement, 16 November 2012, paras. 98, 158. 13 the JCE and characterised the entire Judgement as contradicting “any sense of justice.” 37 In Croatia, the public and the State were galvanized by these verdicts, united first in condemnation and then in celebration of the rulings; in Serbia, the reverse was the case. 38 The other issue that has generated much controversy in recent years, both at the Tribunal and in the public domain, concerns aiding and abetting liability. It turns on whether the actus reus of this mode of liability requires ‘specific direction’, i.e. assistance provided by the accused to those who commit crimes that is specifically directed to aiding the commission of the crimes, or whether it is sufficient to establish knowledge that the aided forces are committing crimes and the aid provided would assist them in doing that. The ICTY Trial Chamber rejected the specific direction standard and convicted Momčilo Perišić, former Chief of Staff of the Yugoslav armed forces, for aiding and abetting Bosnian Serb forces implicated in atrocities in Srebrenica and Sarajevo. 39 The Appeals Chamber, however, upheld the specific direction standard. Considering the nature of the aid and the suspect’s remoteness from the theatre, it concluded that it could not be proven beyond reasonable doubt that the aid provided by Perišić was specifically directed to assist the commission of the crimes, and reversed the conviction. 40 As Marko Milanovic has pointed out, the implication of the approach adopted in the Perišić Appeal Judgement is that “it will be practically impossible to convict under aiding and abetting any political or military leader external to a conflict who is assisting one of the parties even while knowing that they are engaging in mass atrocities, so long as the leader is remote from the actual operations and is not stupid enough to leave a smoking gun behind him.” 41 Adopting this narrow approach to aiding and abetting liability (in conjunction with finding, separately, that the accused did not participate in a JCE) subsequently led the Trial Chamber to acquit Jovica Stanišić and Franko Simatović, former chiefs of Serbia’s State Security Service (DB), who had been involved in setting up and running irregular units implicated in mass atrocities in Bosnia and Croatia. 42 37 Prosecutor v. Gotovina & Markač, IT-60-90-A, Dissenting Opinion of Judge Fausto Pocar, 16 November 2012, paras. 30, 39. 38 In an intriguing twist, when Gotovina arrived in Zagreb to a hero’s welcoming, he did not try to fuel the nationalist passions his acquittal had aroused across the country as many had predicted; instead, he made a surprising appeal for reconciliation and return of Serb refugees to Croatia. B Pavelic, ‘Gotovina: Unlikely Hero of Croat-Serb Dialogue’, BalkanInsight, 7 December 2011, available at http://www.balkaninsight.com/en/article/gotovina-unlikely-hero-of-croat-serb-dialogue (accessed 10 June 2015). 39 Prosecutor v. Perišić, IT-04-81-T, Judgement, 6 September 2011, paras. 1624, 1838. 40 Prosecutor v. Perišić, IT-04-81-A, Judgement, 28 February 2013, paras. 17-74. 41 M Milanovic, ‘The Limits of aiding and Abetting Liability: The ICTY Appeals Chamber Acquits Momcilo Perisic’, EJIL: Talk!, 11 March 2013, available at http://www.ejiltalk.org/the-limits-of-aiding-and-abetting- liability-the-icty-appeals-chamber-acquits-momcilo-perisic/ (accessed 15 June 2015). 42 Prosecutor v. Stanišić & Simatović, IT-03-69-T, Judgement, 30 May 2013, paras. 2356-2363. 14 The controversy was fuelled when Frederik Harhoff, the Danish judge sitting on the ICTY, attacked the President of the Tribunal, Theodor Meron, in a letter that was leaked to the media. The letter accused Judge Meron of exerting pressure on his fellow judges to acquit defendants like Gotovina and Perišić, allegedly acting on behalf of powerful States such as the United States and Israel where the military establishment “felt that the tribunal was getting too close to top-ranking military commanders.” 43 The Harhoff scandal precipitated the most serious crisis in the entire existence of the ICTY. Since then, the tensions in the Tribunal and its jurisprudence on aiding and abetting liability have deepened. The Appeals Chamber in Šainović et al. held that specific direction was not an element of aiding and abetting liability under customary international law and stated that it “unequivocally rejects the approach adopted in the Perišić Appeal Judgement as it is in direct and material conflict with the prevailing jurisprudence on the actus reus of aiding and abetting liability and with customary international law in this regard.” 44 As this article goes to press the much-anticipated decision of the Appeals Chamber in Stanišić & Simatović is pending and the controversy continues. At the same time, shifting the lens from statism to human rights has enabled the Tribunal to extend the normative reach of the law in relation to the substantive offenses within its jurisdiction, making visible and prompting prosecution of certain types of human rights violations that had previously been overlooked or dismissed. In the Nuremberg paradigm, for example, atrocities involving civilians were often viewed as aberrations that were not dictated by the logic of ‘total war’ and in some cases directly conflicted with it by diverting resources away from the front and encumbering the war effort. This is one reason why the Holocaust appeared almost incomprehensible at Nuremberg, although once the shocking nature and scale of these atrocities had been revealed in the course of the proceedings they did move the judges and influenced their sentencing practices. 45 Other atrocities against civilians were typically understood as regrettable side effects of the hostilities, largely unrelated to the conduct of the war itself; as one contemporary commentator put it, “It should be remembered that these crimes are committed chiefly against enemy innocent civilians, non-combatants; that these violations have no relationship with military and strategic considerations.” 46 43 Excerpts of the letter in English were quoted in Marlise Simons, ‘Judge at War Crimes Tribunal Faults Acquittals of Serb and Croat Commanders’, New York Times, 14 June 2014. 44 Prosecutor v. Šainović at al., IT-05-87-A, Judgement, 23 January 2014, paras. 1649-1650. 45 RS Clark, ‘Nuremberg and Tokyo in Contemporary Perspective’, in TLH McCormack and GJ Simpson (eds) The Law of War Crimes: National and International Approaches (Kluwer Law International 1997), 175. 46 MH Myerson, Germany’s War Crimes and Punishment: The Problem of Individual and Collective Criminality (Macmillan Co. of Canada 1944), 230-231. 15 One of the implications of the new paradigm of international justice that emerged in the 1990s was that certain types of human rights violations, which had been consistently neglected in the past, were coming into focus and taken up for prosecution and punishment. Historically, wartime rape and other forms of sexual violence have been viewed as little more than an incidental by-product of armed conflict. The trials after World War II largely neglected abuses involving sexual violence, even in cases where such abuses had a direct relationship to the war effort such as the ‘comfort women’ system run by the Japanese military. 47 Half a century later the United Nations Special Rapporteur for Violence Against Women, Radhika Coomaraswamy, argued that rape was still “the least condemned international crime.” 48 Amid reports of widespread and systematic rape in Bosnia, the Security Council explicitly referenced sexual assaults when it created the ICTY and incorporated rape as a crime against humanity in the Statute. 49 Richard Goldstone notes that the strong condemnation of sexual violence was a key aspect of the motivation for establishing the Tribunal in the first place. 50 Reinforced by sustained attention to such violations in civil society and the media, these developments paved the way for a series of ground-breaking cases that prosecuted various forms of sexual violence as war crimes and crimes against humanity. 51 When evaluating the overall legacy of the Tribunal, observers often emphasise the “huge strides in redressing gender crimes and demonstrating that sexual violence is strategically used as a weapon of war and an instrument of terror. The two Tribunals [for Yugoslavia and Rwanda] have together rendered Judgments recognizing rape and other forms of sexual violence as crimes against humanity, war crimes, instruments of genocide, means of persecution, and forms of torture, particularly sexual violence manifested in the form of rape, sexual slavery, forced nudity, and sexual mutilation.” 52 Such developments in the law have to 47 See G Hicks, The Comfort Women: Japan’s Brutal Regime of Enforced Prostitution in the Second World War (Norton 19950; C Chinkin, ‘Women’s International Tribunal on Japanese Military Sexual Slavery’ (2001) 95(2) AJ Int’l L 335-341. 48 Special Rapporteur on Violence Against Women, Preliminary Report on Violence Against Women, Its Causes and Consequences, UN Doc E/CN4/1995/42 (1994), para. 42. 49 See Report of the Secretary General Pursuant to Paragraph 2 of Security Council Resolution 808, UN Doc S/25704 (1993), paras. 9, 11, 48, 88, 108; ICTY Statute, Article 5(g). 50 RJ Goldstone, ‘Prosecuting Rape as a War Crime’ (2002) 34 Case W Res J Int’l L 277-285, 278. 51 See, e.g., Prosecutor v. Furundžija, IT-95-17/1-T, Trial Judgement, 10 December 1998 (rape as a violation of the laws or customs of war); Prosecutor v. Mucić et al., IT-96-21-T, 16 November 1998 (rape constitutes torture and a grave breach of the Geneva Conventions); Prosecutor v Kunarac et al., IT-96-23/1-T, 22 February 2001 (rape as an instrument of terror, a violation of the laws or customs of war and a crime against humanity). 52 KD Askin, ‘Reflections on Some of the Most Significant Achievements of the ICTY’ (2002/3) New Eng L Rev 903-914, 909-910. See generally KD Askin, ‘Prosecuting Wartime Rape and Other Gender-Related Crimes under International Law: Extraordinary Advances, Enduring Obstacles’ (2003) 21(2) Berkeley J Int’l L 288-349. 16 be understood in terms of the Yugoslav Tribunal’s self-conscious conception of the relationship between international law and shifting paradigms of security. In this respect, when examining challenges to the Tribunal’s jurisdiction in its very first case, the judges held that “a state-sovereignty-oriented approach has been gradually supplanted by a human-rights- oriented approach.” 53 4. International Justice and the Liberal Peace Adapting and developing the law is of little significance if the former Israeli Ambassador to the United States, Abba Edan, is right that international law is the law “the wicked do not obey and the righteous do not enforce.” 54 Compliance and enforcement have indeed been central problems for the Yugoslav Tribunal over the past two decades. Especially with respect to arresting and transferring suspects to The Hague, the interests of States often appeared to trump human rights considerations and obstructed the course of justice. It could be argued that the problems of compliance and enforcement manifest a broader set of tensions between statism and human rights, which arise when international interventions associated with the liberal peace are pursued alongside international justice. These tensions are most clearly expressed in the interactions of international justice with security instruments at the sharp end of the liberal peace, although they can also be detected elsewhere in the toolbox of liberal peace interventionism. The argument is elaborated by examining three types of security instruments that have been deployed concurrently with international justice in the Balkans: peacemaking, peacekeeping and peacebuilding. As already noted, the establishment of the Yugoslav Tribunal advanced a distinctive approach to security by recasting individuals as the referent object of security and human rights violations as a threat to security, and by reframing as means for promoting security the enforcement of rights, prosecution and punishment of perpetrators, and suppression of mutually exclusive nationalisms and narratives of collective guilt. And yet, at key junctures when international justice was supposed to promote this approach, other security instruments were employed by the international community that have often contradicted and undermined its logic and purposes. One such juncture was Dayton. Peacemaking and international justice initially appeared to be mutually reinforcing rather than conflicting. The ICTY indicted the 53 Tadić Jurisdiction Appeal, para 97. 54 Quoted in WK Lietzau, ‘Combating Terrorism: The Consequences of Moving from Law Enforcement to War’, in D Wippman and M Evangelista (eds) New Wars, New Laws? Applying the Laws of War in 21 st Century Conflicts (Transnational Publishers 2005). 17 most senior leaders of the Bosnian Serbs, Radovan Karadžić and Ratko Mladić, in the run-up to the peace negotiations at Dayton. The US envoy leading the talks, Richard Holbrooke, has argued that the indictments made the job of the negotiators easier by allowing them to marginalise Karadžić and Mladić. 55 The Dayton Accords were concluded in November 1995 and incorporated provisions requiring the parties to cooperate with the Tribunal. 56 The international community was desperate for peace in Bosnia and negotiated a deal that ended the hostilities by effectively rewarding the extremists responsible for human rights abuses and legitimising the outcome of ethnic cleansing. The Dayton Accords created a patchwork of ethnic entities and enclaves and set up a framework of power-sharing between the three ‘constituent peoples’: Bosniaks, Croats and Serbs. If the pursuit of international justice was intended to vindicate human rights, promote accountability and suppress nationalism, the international community appeared to be doing the opposite at Dayton – even as it demanded cooperation with the Tribunal on paper. By entrenching ethnic divides and elites in power structures instead of creating the conditions for dismantling them, the settlement has engendered a sort of permanent crisis and two decades later it still requires the presence of peacekeepers. As Timothy Donais notes, the result is that “the country’s politics remains largely segregated along ethnic lines, nationalist rhetoric continues to be the key currency of Bosnian political life, and the practice of reaping the spoils of office for the benefit of self or party continues to be the norm.” 57 The Dayton agreement affected the prospects for human rights and accountability in Bosnia and the wider region in several ways. The tensions between the constitutional order constructed at Dayton and international human rights standards have been highlighted by the European Court of Human Rights. In Sejdić and Finci it held that Bosnia’s constitutional provisions preventing persons not affiliated with one of the three ‘constituent peoples’ to stand for election to the House of Peoples and the Presidency amounted to ethnic discrimination. 58 In the first years after Dayton, suspects like Karadžić and Maldić were allowed to move freely despite ICTY arrest warrants. In fact, Karadžić has insisted that in 55 ‘Seven Questions: Richard Holbrooke on Radovan Karadzic’, Foreign Policy, 24 July 2008, available at http://foreignpolicy.com/2008/07/24/seven-questions-richard-holbrooke-on-radovan-karadzic/ (accessed 15 June 2015). 56 See The Dayton Peace Agreement, General Framework Agreement for Peace in Bosnia and Herzegovina, 21 November 1995, U.S. Dept. State Dispatch Supp. 7(1). 57 T Donais, ‘Power Politics and the Rule of Law in Post-Dayton Bosnia’ (2013) 7(2) Studies in Social Justice 189-210, 202. 58 Sejdić and Finci v. Bosnia and Herzegovina, App. Nos. 27966/06 and 34836/06, Judgment of the Grand Chamber, 22 December 2009. 18 1996 Holbrooke made an agreement with him to withdraw from public life in exchange for immunity from prosecution. 59 Holbrooke denied the allegations but other credible sources have corroborated them and suspicions persist. 60 Dayton also had the effect of strengthening the repressive regimes of Slobodan Milošević and Franjo Tuđman, both of which had been implicated in wartime atrocities. By entrenching Milošević (hailed as a ‘peacemaker’ 61 at that time) and neglecting the brewing crisis in Kosovo, the settlement paved the way for the campaign of ethnic cleansing in the province that prompted the 1999 NATO bombing of Yugoslavia. Peacekeeping operations have also been disruptive for the logic and aims of international justice. The underlying statist understandings of security and stability that often inform such operations have tended to contradict and undermine the human rights approach. One expression of these tensions has involved a clash between force protection and human rights enforcement. States that had earlier spearheaded the effort to establish the Yugoslav Tribunal, such as the United States, became reluctant to put the lives of their soldiers in Bosnia at risk in order to apprehend suspects wanted by the ICTY: “With the memory of the eighteen U.S. soldiers killed in Somalia in 1993 still fresh, the U.S Joint Chiefs of Staff had signed off on the [Dayton] peace agreement only after receiving assurances from the White House that U.S. troops would not be ordered to hunt down war criminals.” 62 In line with force protection priorities, in the initial years NATO peacekeepers in Bosnia were instructed to take into custody individuals indicted by the ICTY only if they surrendered or happened to stumble upon international forces. Another example is the Kosovo crisis. The problems with the NATO bombing of Yugoslavia from a human rights perspective are well-known: use of cluster bombs and depleted uranium missiles; bombing the Serbian television and accidentally bombing the Chinese embassy in Belgrade; air strikes that caused civilian casualties and accelerated ethnic cleansing on the ground. 63 At a time when the NATO air campaign appeared to be losing momentum and public support, indicting Milošević was embraced as a way of legitimating the war and putting more pressure on Belgrade: “After years of refusing to turn over sensitive 59 See Prosecutor v. Karadžić, IT-95-5/18-AR73.4, Decision on Karadžić’s Appeal of Trial Chamber’s Decision on Alleged Holbrooke Agreement, 12 October 2009. 60 M Simmons, ‘Study Backs Bosnian Serb’s Claim of Immunity’, New York Times, 21 March 2009. 61 See A LeBor, ‘Milosevic the Peacemaker’, IWPR, TU332, 7 November 2003, available at https://iwpr.net/global-voices/comment-milosevic-peacemaker (accessed 15 June 2015). 62 C Sudetic, ‘The Reluctant Gendarme’, Atlantic Monthly, April 2000. 63 See Independent International Commission on Kosovo, The Kosovo Report: Conflict, International Response, Lessons Learned (OUP 2000). 19 intelligence data to the Tribunal in order to protect “sources and methods,” the United States and Britain were hurriedly handing over reams of satellite imagery, telephone intercepts, and other top secret information to the Prosecutor to make the case against Milosevic.” 64 Milošević and four members of his regime were indicted on 22 May 1999, sixty days into the seventy-eight day NATO air campaign. 65 The potential of international justice to advance human rights, promote accountability and defuse ethnic tensions was overshadowed by the effects of NATO air strikes and peacekeeping, which pulled in the opposite direction. The bombing of Yugoslavia had the effect of radicalizing Serbian nationalism and fuelling its narratives of victimization, reinforcing the traction of collectivist framings of the conflict and crimes in Serbian politics and society. When Serb forces pulled out of Kosovo, KFOR deployed some 40,000 peacekeepers to the province; their presence, however, did not prevent ethnic cleansing targeting the remaining Serbs and revenge attacks against Albanians accused of collaboration. The Kosovo Human Losses database at the Humanitarian Law Center (Belgrade and Pristina) has documented more than 1,600 casualties in Kosovo for the first year and a half of international peacekeeping (June 1999-December 2000), of which around a quarter are Albanian and the rest are Serb, Roma and other minorities, including many disappearances. 66 This high level of casualties at a time when peacekeepers had been deployed in large numbers reflects the reluctance of KFOR to send a clear message early on, particularly to the Kosovo Liberation Army (KLA), that international forces would not tolerate human rights abuses. The abuses and entrenchment of the KLA in power structures that occurred at that time have had far-reaching consequences for accountability by instilling fear in victims and witnesses, who have often been reluctant to come forward and testify in cases involving KLA members at the ICTY and at Kosovo’s hybrid courts for war crimes. The most significant peacebuilding instrument employed by the international community in the region is the Stabilisation and Association Process (SAP) for the Western Balkans, a regional policy framework established by the European Union (EU) in 1999 for the countries of the former Yugoslavia (excluding Slovenia) and Albania. The aim of the instrument is to promote stabilisation through a process of progressive partnership with these countries that includes the prospect of association and, eventually, accession to the EU. Full cooperation with the ICTY was set as a key condition for moving forward in the SAP, 64 MP Scharf, ‘The Legacy of the Milosevic Trial’ (2003) 37(4) New Eng L Rev 915-933, 924. 65 Prosecutor v. Milošević et al., IT-99-36, Indictment (Kosovo), 22 May 1999. 66 Data on file with the author. 20 alongside demonstrating respect for minority rights, offering real opportunities for displaced persons and refugees to return home and demonstrating a clear commitment to regional cooperation. The war crimes conditionality has been one of the most contentious aspects of the SAP and has often dominated the politics of EU integration in the region. 67 It was crucial for ensuring that all suspects sought by the Tribunal from the original list of 161 indicted persons were eventually apprehended and transferred to The Hague to stand trial, a lengthy and difficult process that was completed in 2011 with the arrests of Ratko Mladić and Goran Hadžić. At the same time, the ICTY conditionality was applied rather unevenly in the SAP, raising the issue of selectivity, and created divisions in the EU as some Member States insisted on a principled approach while others preferred compromise and accommodation. The tensions were expressed most clearly when the EU was using the war crimes issue to advance strategic considerations for stability and public order at the expense of the SAP’s normative commitments to accountability and human rights. 68 In the case of Croatia, the EU suspended accession negotiations over its failure to apprehend Gotovina and reopened them only after the Tribunal had been satisfied with Croatia’s efforts to cooperate. In the case of Serbia, however, the ICTY conditionality was repeatedly compromised and used by the EU as a bargaining chip in order to influence political developments in the country and to shape its response to Kosovo’s declaration of independence. Jelena Subotić observes that in that context “the issue of justice for crimes against humanity became an issue of the lowest order, a matter of deal making and compromise setting, removed as far as possible from the ideas and norms of dealing with the past.” 69 With the completion of the Tribunal’s remaining cases in sight, the EU has started to shift attention in the SAP from international justice to domestic prosecution of war crimes. So far, however, the focus has been on building capacity for conducting such trials at the various domestic and hybrid courts in the region, rather than requiring applicant countries to demonstrate effective investigation and prosecution of war crimes. 67 See J Batt and J Obradovic-Wochnik (eds) War Crimes, Conditionality, and EU Integration in the Western Balkans, ISS Chaillot Paper 116, June 2009. 68 See I Rangelov, ‘Democracy or Stability? European Approaches to Justice in Peace and Transitional Processes’ (2014) 5(2) Global Policy 191-200. 69 J Subotić, Hijacked Justice: Dealing with the Past in the Balkans (Cornell UP 2009), 81. 21 5. Conclusion The pursuit of international justice in the former Yugoslavia half a century after the Nuremberg trials signals a shift in security paradigms from statism to human rights, while also giving rise to deep tensions and contradictions between them. Judicial practice at the ICTY has tended to advance this shift by adapting and developing the law in line with a human rights approach to security but it has not been immune to setbacks and interference, especially when the jurisprudence of the Tribunal has appeared to challenge entrenched interests and practices of States. To the extent that the exercise of international justice depends on States for enforcement and for its continued existence, the Yugoslav case suggests that there are inherent tensions between statism and human rights that cannot be addressed by judicial bodies alone, in the absence of a parallel shift in the security thinking and practices of States. These tensions have affected the ability of international justice to offer a security strategy in the Balkans in important ways. The potential of international justice to promote a rights-based approach to security has been repeatedly compromised when liberal peace interventions in the region have been working at cross-purposes with international justice. Key security instruments that have been employed by the international community in the Balkans, such as peacemaking, peacekeeping and peacebuilding, reflect a set of state-centric ideas about security and involve related security practices that often disrupt the pursuit of international justice and undermine its logic and purposes. The interactions of international justice with such instruments could be understood as a series of tensions between elite- mediated peace deals, force protection priorities and an overarching concern for stability, on the one side, and normative commitments to promote accountability and enforce human rights, on the other. When key international actors engaged in the Balkans have viewed stability and justice as competing security strategies, the former has tended to trump the latter in practice. As a security culture, the liberal peace in its current form involves a set of state-centric ideas and practices that cannot be easily reconciled with the distinctive rights-centric conception of security advanced by international justice and often undermine its logic and purposes. More research is needed to illuminate the complex relationship between liberal peace interventions and justice instruments in situations where both are deployed. The Balkan case, however, calls into question the widespread assumption that transitional justice is an integral part of liberal peacebuilding and suggests that analysis along those lines may be misguided and counterproductive. Finally, the tensions between international justice and the 22 liberal peace raise questions about one of the standard lines of critique of liberal peacebuilding, which argues that the problem with the liberal peace is that it is too liberal. If ‘liberal’ means treating individuals as the referent object of security and placing human rights at the heart of the means and ends of public security provision, the problem with the liberal peace might well be the opposite. Rangelov_Justice as a Security Strategy _Cover Rangelov_Justice as a Security Strategy_Author_2016 work_h4zbadklhjaitpp63f7skobmau ---- 73 CRIMINAL JUSTICE SYSTEM OF CHILDREN: AN OVERVIEW RESTORATIVE JUSTICE CONCEPT IN INDONESIA AND OTHER COUNTRIES Loura Hardjaloka Bahar & Partners E-mail: loura.hardjaloka@gmail.com/loura@baharandpartners.com Abstract The pattern of repression in Act No. 3 of 1997 has been changed to a restorative justice through diversion in Act No. 11 of 2012 considering the repressive punishment does not reduce the number of juvenile criminal but increasing. The purpose of this research is to examine the concept of restorative justice in order to see the form of the application of the concept of restorative justice in Indonesia and other countries. The method of this research is judicial normative with secondary data and analyzed based on content analysis. Based on this research, the concept of restorative justice both in Indonesia and other countries is applied through a diversion for the best interest of children (actor), which are implemented in the form of mediation so the children can take their responsibilities for their actions without court trial. Keywords: juvenile justice system, comparative studies, restorative justice, diversion Abstrak Pola represif dalam Undang-Undang Nomor 3 Tahun 1997 telah bergeser menjadi keadilan restoratif melalui diversi dalam Undang-Undang Nomor 11 Tahun 2012 mengingat pemidanaan represif tidak me- nurunkan angka pidana anak tetapi justru meningkat. Tujuan penulisan ialah mengkaji konsep keadilan restoratif sehingga dapat dilihat bentuk penerapan konsep keadilan restoratif di Indonesia dan Negara lain. Metode penulisan yang digunakan ialah yuridis normatif dengan data sekunder dan dianalisis berdasarkan content analysis. Berdasarkan hasil penelitian, konsep keadilan restoratif baik di Indonesia dan Negara lainnya dilakukan melalui diversi untuk kepentingan terbaik (pelaku) anak yang diimple- mentasikan dalam bentuk mediasi sehingga anak dapat mempertanggungjawabkan perbuatannya tanpa melalui pengadilan. Kata kunci: sistem peradilan pidana anak, studi komparasi, restorative justice, diversi Preface Children Criminal Justice System (SPPA) is basically aimed at the welfare of the child, as defined in the United Nations Standard Minimum Rules for the Administration of Juvenile Justice.1 As a country that is part of the Convention on the Rights of the Child (Convention on the Rights of the Child), Indonesia also provide special pro- tection to children in conflict with the law through the establishment of Law No. 3 of 1997 about Juvenile Court (Law 3/1997) and Law No. 23 of 2002 about Child Protection. 1 Vanessa Coppins, Sharon Casey, dan Allan Campbell, “The Child’s Best Interest: A Review of Australian Juve- nile Justice Legislation”, The Open Criminology Journal, Vol. 1 No. August 2011, page 23. SPPA in Law 3/1997 do not provide opti- mal protection for the child considering the law still using formal juridical approach by empha- sizing punishment (retributive) that could po- tentially restrict the freedom and independence depriving children.2 The concept of punishment contained in Law 3/1997 not make the number of juvenile criminal diminishing, but increasing from year to year, as can be seen in Figure 1 below.3 2 Sufriadi Pinim dan Erasmus Napitupulu, 2013, Studi Atas Praktik-Praktik Peradilan Anak di Jakarta, Jakarta: Insti- ture for Criminal Justice Reform, page 14. 3 Yutirsa Yunus, “Analisis Konsep Restorative Justice Me- lalui Sistem Diversi Dalam Sistem Peradilan Pidana Anak Di Indonesia”, Jurnal Rechts Vinding, Vol. 2 No. 2nd Au- mailto:loura.hardjaloka@gmail.com/loura@baharandpartners.com 74 Jurnal Dinamika Hukum Vol. 15 No. 1, January 2015 Figure 1. Number of Child Prisoners in 2010 - 2013 Overcome the weaknesses of Law 3/1997, was issued Law No. 11 of 2012 on Juvenile Jus- tice System (Law 11/2012), which uses the ap- proach of restorative justice through diversion system. Diversion system is the transfer of the settlement of the child to outside the criminal justice process that involves a dialogue with victims, perpetrators, law enforcement offici- als, and the public. The concept of diversion gi- ven by Law 11/2012 which is different from the law 3/1997 only allows versioned conducted by the investigator based on the discretionary au- thority by submitting the return of the child to the parent, guardian, or foster parents. Imple- mentation of restorative justice is not only app- lied in Indonesia, but also in different countries applied for criminal cases in children and adoles- cents as in Illinois, Germany, Canada, Austria, Poland, and Spain. Problem Based on background above, therefore this research is intended to answer the problem as follows: first, how is the concept of resto- rative justice for children in conflict with the law in Law 11/2012; and second, how is the con- cept of restorative justice for children in con- gust 2013, Jakarta: Pusat Penelitian dan Pengembangan Sistem Hukum Nasional Badan Pembinaan Hukum Nasio- nal, page 232. 4 Eva Achjani Zulfa, “Keadilan Restoratif dan Revitalisasi Lembaga Adat di Indonesia”, Jurnal Kriminologi Indone- sia, Vol. 6 No. 2nd August 2010, page 185 5 Kristine Buffington, Carly Dierkhising, dan Shawn Marsh, “Ten Things Every Juvenile Court Should Know About flict with the law in the regulations in other countries. Research Methods This research is using normative juridical approach. Normative research is a legal research using secondary data including legislation, books, and research literature related to the re- search topic. Furthermore, the data were ana- lyzed with content analysis to analyze the for- mulation of the problem and then made a con- clusion and suggestion. Discussion The concept of Restorative Justice through Di- version in Law 11/2012 in Indonesia Children facing conflict with the law in Article 1 point 3 Law 11/2012, is a children at least 12 years old but not yet 18 years old. Con- cept and theories of punishment continues to develop. The goal is to address children in con- flict with the law. Starting from the traditional theory of justice that includes retributive justi- ce, restitutive justice, to the modern theory of justice such as restorative justice.4 Most of the criminal law experts, psycho- logists, and child behavior experts consider that the theory of restorative justice and a good right to be applied in the juvenile criminal justice sys- tem.5 The involvement of the parties is a major prerequisite to the implementation of the juve- nile criminal justice system based on restorative justice. The roles of the parties in criminal jus- tice-based subsidiary of restorative justice is as follows in Table 2.6 Law 11/2012, being passed on July 30, 2012, has embraced the paradigm of restorative justice through diversion system. As for the substance of the changes in Law 11/2012 of the most fundamental is expressly settings on res- torative justice and diversion intended to avoid Trauma and Delinquency”, Juvenile and Family Court Journal, Vol. 61 No. 3rd Agustus 2010, page 18. 6 Gordon Bazemore dan Susan Day, “Restoring the Ba- lance: Juvenile and Community Justice”, Journal of the Office of Juvenile Justice and Deliquency Prevention, Vol. 3 No. 1st March 2010, page 9. 0 1000 2000 3000 4000 2010 2011 2012 2013 547 3672 3635 2214 Criminal Justice System of Children: An Overview Restorative Justice Concept... 75 and keep children out of the judicial process so as to avoid stigmatization of children in conflict with the law and is expected child can return to the social environment reasonable. Table 1: The Differences between Retributive Justice, Restitutive Justice, and Restorative Justice7 Retributive Justice Restitutive Justice Restorative Justice  Emphasizing justice to re- tailation;  Children are in a position as an object;  Settlement of legal issues imbalanced. Emphasizes equity compen- sation  Emphasizing justice in the repair/recovery state;  Oriented to the victim;  Provide opportunities for actors to express annoyance to the victim and responsible;  Provide an opportunity for the offender and the victim to meet in order to reduce hostility and hatred;  Restoring balance in society;  Involving community members in an effort to elections. Source: Rosida Table 2: Role of Parties in the Restorative Justice Model for Children Criminalization through Accountability Rehabilitation through Competence Development Improving Public Sector Security Actors Contributing actively to recover losses suffered by the victim and the community and must meet the victims. Actively involved as a human re- sources who should improve the quality of life in the community and have a stock of knowledge, ex- perience, and self-esteem as a pro- ductive human resources to carry out positive activities. Involved in the development of self-competence and restorati- on activities; Increasing self- control, to make new friends, and active in the organization. Victim Involved in the development of self-competence and restoration activities; Increasing self-con- trol, to make new friends, and active in the organization. Providing input to the process of rehabilitation; Suggest the imple- menttation of social services for offenders; Participate in associa- tion victim or victim awareness training to staff and actors. Participating in creating sustai- nable security in the public sec- tor; Support other victims. Community Acting as a mediator; Developing social services and the opening of employment for offenders; Assis- tance to victims and provide sup- port to the actors in carrying out its obligations. Develop new employment oppor- tunities for young people to incre- ase productivity, competence, and a sense of belonging (self of belo- nging). Provide protection to the per- petrators, mentoring, and pro- vide input to the child criminal system in order to provide se- curity to the perpetrator; Over- come the problems that exist in the community related to kena- lana children. Professionals Facilitators of the mediation; En- suring restoration actions (by providing a way for actors to rai- se funds for restoration); Deve- lop creative community/commu- nity social services; To educate the public in accordance with the role. Developing new roles for actors so as to make them learn and demon- strate competencies learned; As- sess and build the strength of youth and the community; Develop cooperation between communi- ties. Accompanying the school and community to control and main- tain the offender in the com- munity; Develop the ability to prevent repeat offenders ac- tions. Source: Bazemore and Day The use of restorative justice approach in the juvenile criminal justice system defined in Article 5 paragraph (1) of Law 11/2012 that the juvenile criminal justice system shall prioritize restorative justice approach. Restorative justice is the completion of criminal cases involving per- petrators, victims, families’ perpetrator/victim, and other relevant parties to work together to find a fair settlement with emphasis on restoring 7 Nikmah Rosidah, “Pembaharuan Ide Diversi dalam Imple- mentasi Sistem Peradilan Anak di Indonesia”, Jurnal back to the original state, and not retaliation. Restorative justice approach is then implemen- ted through a system of diversion. Diversion is the transfer of the settlement of the child to the criminal justice process outside the criminal jus- tice process. Philosophically, the concept of di- version based on the opinion that the court will give stigmatization of children for their actions as a child is considered evil, so it is better to Masalah-Masalah Hukum, Vol. 41 No. April 2012, page 200. 76 Jurnal Dinamika Hukum Vol. 15 No. 1, January 2015 avoid it out of the criminal justice system.8 Di- version is granted because it fit with the philo- sophy of juvenile criminal justice system to pro- tect and rehabilitate child criminals.9 In addi- tion, the diversion is also performed as an actor prevention of child become adult criminals. Child prevention efforts that brought law enfor- cement officers to take discretionary authority or in the United States is often referred to as deinstitutionalization of the formal criminal jus- tice system.10 Diversion through the concept of resto- rative justice in Law 11/2012 is appropriate and consistent with the goals of diversion contained in the Beijing Rules namely: (i) In order to avoid arrest; (ii) to avoid stamp/stigmatized as cri- minals; (iii) to improve the skills of life for the child actors; (iv) that the perpetrators respon- sible for their actions; (v) to prevent the repe- tition of crime; (vi) to promote the necessary in- terventions for victims and perpetrators, with- out having to go through a formal process; (vii) the program will also prevent the diversion of children follow the justice system.11 Further, in Article 5 paragraph (3) of Law 11/2012 mentions, that the compulsory diver- sion system to be at the stage of investigation, prosecution, and trial. This liability is increa- singly defined through various provisions that oblige the law enforcement agencies include the investigator, the public investigator, and the judge to seek diversion, as follows: Table 4: Liability for Diversion Efforts Law Enforcement under Law 11/2012 Provision Law 11/2012 Liability for Diversion Efforts Article 7 Start checking at all levels of investigation, prosecution, and examination of the matter in court is obliged to seek diversion. Article 28 The investigator is obliged to seek diversion within 7 days after being found with the child. Article 37 The public prosecutor is obliged to seek diversion. Article 49 The judge is obliged to seek diversion. Source: Processed under Law 11/2012 Under Law 11/2012, the diversion is done through deliberations involving the child and the parent/guardian, the victim and/or parent/ guardian, the civic, and the supervising social worker professionals. In case necessary, the deliberations can also involve social welfare per- sonnel, and/or the community. As the process of diversion in a nutshell can be shown in Figure 2. Diversion can be carried out by the com- munity in a way to reconcile both parties i.e. victim and perpetrator. However, diversion can only be done with the permission of the victims and the families of the victim, as well as the willingness of the offender and his family. At- tempts to resolve the matter outside of court should take precedence, even the mediation process was still possible even though the mat- ter had been entered in court. The Tribunal jud- ges who adjudicate must facilitate when reques- ted by the parties, and if the litigants agrees to terms the Council immediately halted. Here it is seen that the criminal law as a remedial abso- lutely ultimatum applied. 8 Robert John Zagar, “Delinquency Best Treatments: How to Divert Youths from Violence While Saving Lives and Detention Costs”, Behavioral Sciences & The Law, Vol. 31 No. 3rd June 2013, page 385. 9 Douglas Abrams, “A Primer on Juvenile Protective Le- gislation”, Juvenile and Family Court Journal, Vol. 65 No. 3rd September 2014, page 25. 10 Shelly Jackson, Janet Warren, dan Jessica Jones Coburn, “A Community-Based Model for Remediating Juveniles Adjudicated Incompetent to Stand Trial: Feedback From Youth, Attorneys, and Judges”, Juvenile and Family Court Journal, Vol. 65 No. 2nd January 2014, page 25. 11 John Muncie, “International Juvenile (in) Justice: Penal Severity and Rights Compliance”, International Journal for Crime, Justice and Social Democracy, Vol. 2 No. 2nd July 2013, page 55. Criminal Justice System of Children: An Overview Restorative Justice Concept... 77 Figure 2. Diversion Process under Law 11/2012 Source: Processed Under Law 11/2012 The SPPA Concept of Restorative Justice in Other Countries The SPPA concept of restorative justice in Indonesia also set up in other countries like Illi- nois, Germany, Canada, Austria, Poland, and Spain. As for the age limit for children who are dealing with the law in those countries is as follows: Table 5: Limitation Age of Children dealing with Law in Other Country Age (Years) Country 14-18 Germany, Austria 10-16 Illionois, United States 12-18 Canada 16-18 Spain 15-17 Poland Source: Processed from Several Sources The SPPA Concept of Restorative Justice in Illinois, United States Provisions of the SPPA in Illinois, the Uni- ted States set in the Illinois Juvenile Court Act of 1987 which amended through the Juvenile Justice Reform Provisions of 1998. As for such a significant change is the adoption of restorative justice or negotiations (balanced or restorative 12 Korey Wahwassuck, “The New Face of Justice: Joint Tri- bal-State Jurisdiction”, Juvenile and Family Court Jour- nal, Vol. 60 No. 1st December 2009, page 15. 13 Erna Olafson dan Julie Kenniston, “Obtaining Informa- tion From Children In the Justice System”, Juvenile and justice orientation). The implementation of res- torative justice through versioned also applied in 17 areas in Illinois but not yet in the entire region.12 The implementation of the principle of ba- lanced and restorative justice seeks to balance all the affected parties of any crimes committed by children, as victims, perpetrators, and com- munities. The purpose of the concept of resto- rative justice or negotiations (balanced or res- torative justice orientation) is as follows in Tab- le 6.13 The Prosecutor in children’s condem- nation will provide the opportunity for the de- fendant to undergo a program of restorative jus- tice through the system are versioned. As for restorative justice programs through the diver- sion system offered in Illinois, among other com- munity mediation panels, negotiations between the victim and offender, social services pro- grams, restitution, and other programs that can provide opportunities for children to be respon- sible for his actions at once aimed at rehabili- tation and restoration without the need through the judiciary.14 Community mediation panels Family Court Journal, Vol. 59 No. 4th November 2008, page 80. 14 Illinois Criminal Justice Commission, 2012, Policies and Procedures of The Illinois Juvenile Justice System, Chi- cago: Illinois Criminal Justice Information Authority, pa- ge 10-12. 78 Jurnal Dinamika Hukum Vol. 15 No. 1, January 2015 forms by the country’s lawyers to provide an op- portunity for members of the community to be involved in child delinquency which is through community involvement is expected to help the child understand the seriousness of the acts that he did, and the effects of his actions to the public. Table 6. The Purpose of Restorative Justice Concept in Illinois Form as Accountability Security Community Development of Competencies The concept of restorative justice or negotia- tions (balanced or restorative justice orien- tation) is intended to provide the opportu- nity for the child to being able the perpetra- tors responsible for the crimes that have been made and simultaneously provide the opportunity for players to improve his offen- se. The concept of restorative justice or negotiations (balanced or restorative justice orientation) is keep the security community. The security community can be created with this principle by means of building relationships and strengthening communities to take on the role for the welfare of its members. The concept of restorative justi- ce or negotiations (balanced or restorative justice orientation) seeks to improve the competen- cies of competence the princi- pals that can be useful for social life. Sumber: Olafson and Kenniston The SPPA Concept of Restorative Justice in Germany Children’s condemnation in Germany is re- gulated in the Code of Criminal Law (article 46a), the Code of Criminal Procedure (article 153a) and the Juvenile Justice Act 1953 as amended Youth Court Law Amendment Act 1990. Article 45 and article 47 of the Juvenile Justice Act 1953 as amended Youth Court Law Amendment Act 1990 makes it clear that the Prosecutor and judge must consider measures of non-condemnation compared to the overthrow of the criminal. In Brandenberg, the Prosecutor must refer any case children toward good mediation out- side the courts or special case of children use a mediator to conduct mediation in juvenile court. If the mediation is successful, then the Prosecutor will terminate the case in respect of crimes committed are not serious, while serious crime for which the perpetrators have signi- ficant criminal records then the public prose- cutor must still process such still pay attention to the results of mediation.15 The SPPA Concept of Restorative Justice in Canada Section 717 Criminal Code and The Young Offenders Act 4 of 1984 set about restorative justice through versioned on children’s condem- nation. The existence of such provisions effect- ed because the police and the Court considers criminal justice was not in accordance with the principle of the best interests of the child or the public. Therefore, it takes a step outside the court that can encourage the involvement of families and communities in solving cases, i.e. through restorative justice programs. These are some programs restorative justice for criminal offenders, as follows:16 Table 7: Restorative Justice Programs for Children in Canada Program Description Pre-Charge Restorative Program A move made after a child caught doing the deed, but on condition that certain criminal police would not specify the perpetrators as a defendant. As for the conditions that must be met is that the offender must be willing to participate in the pre-charge restorative programs defined as a form of accountability. In addition, the police can also recommend family actors to participate in this program. Post-Charge Restorative Program A move made after the offender has children is officially designated as a defendant in a court procedure but has not started yet. 15 Arthur Hartmann, “Victim-Offender-Mediation in Germa- ny”, British Journal of Community Justice, Vol. 6 No. 2nd April 2008, page 145. 16 Andrew Becroft, “Children and Young People in Conflict With The Law: Asking The Hard Questions”, Juvenile and Family Court Journal, Vol. 57 No. 4th September 2006, page 25. Criminal Justice System of Children: An Overview Restorative Justice Concept... 79 Post Sentence Program A move made after the offender has been sentenced by a juvenile court. In the verdict, the judge may decide that the offender participate in certain programs as part of the punishment, or in addition to punishment. Youth Justice Committees Juvenile Court Committee is one of the program’s implementation of the principles of restorative justice in the criminal process. In this case the members of the Committee met with the victim, the defendant’s son, and parents (both the defendant and the victim) to negotiate the best course of action that can be performed by actors in order to improve his offense. In addition, the Committee also takes care of the implementation program of pre-and post-charge given to the perpetrators. Further, the Committee will ensure there is community support to child abusers by means of involving actors in social activities and schedule of certain members of the public to provide mentoring and supervision. The Committee will also assist coordination between child protection agencies by the SPPA. Restorative Conferences Restorative talks provided for in Section 19-Young Offenders Act 1984. The talks are aimed at increasing the involvement of the victim and members of the community in the criminal case of the child. As for the negotiations are negotiations involving restorative principals, orban, and members of the community and produce a verdict which is to provide compensation to victims for acts committed by the offender. As for the kinds of negotiations can be restorative (i) family group conferences; (ii) youth justice committee, (iii) reconciliation between the victim and the offender; (iv) sentencing circles17; (v) community accountability panels18; and (vi) inter-agency case conferences. As for the purpose of these negotiations is to provide opinions on the type of the corresponding punishment that can be meted out to the perpetrators. Source: Becroft The SPPA Concept of Restorative Justice in Austria Children’s condemnation Austria is regu- lates in article 7 and article 8 the Juvenile Act of 1988. The implementation of restorative jus- tice in Austria is carried out through the media- tion of the penal (Victim-Offender Mediation) in which the final outcome of mediation was repor- ted to the public prosecutor. Mediation can be done directly, where victims and perpetrators are present together, or indirectly, where the victim and the offender does not meet the facili- tated by the mediator (shuttle mediation).1917 The SPPA Concept of Restorative Justice in Po- land Poland does not control the restorative justice expressly in the Juvenile Justice Act, ho- wever indirectly steel penal mediation for crimi- nal offenders committed by juvenile court judge or by a registered mediator. Mediation is done in the early stages of the trial in order to reach an agreement on how the offender can account for his actions. The results of the mediation will be strengthened in the judge’s ruling. Results on mediation in General may include actions that can be performed by the offender accountable for his actions but still has elements of edu- cational, non-conditional, or returned to the pa- rents.20 The SPPA Concept of Restorative Justice in Spain The application of the concept of restora- tive justice through versioned in system child- ren’s condemnation is regulated in Law 4/92 as amended by Law 5/2000 regarding in criminal justice system for children. Basically penal me- diation can be used in 2 ways:21 17 In this case, victim, offender, family, and community members meet the judges, lawyers, and others to give recommendation for the judge about the kind of punish- ment that should be accepted by the offender. 18 A negotiation which was attended by community leaders, perpetrators, victims (if wanted), and parents actors to reach an agreement fixes the error. 19 Gordon Bazemore, Jay Zaslaw, dan Danielle Riester, “Be- hind the Walls and Beyond: Restorative Justice, Instru- mental Communities, and Effective Residential Treat- ment”, Juvenile and Family Court Journal, Vol. 56 No. 1 January 2005, page 60. 20 Anna Mestitz, “Organisational Features of Victim-Of- fender Mediation with Youth Offenders in Europe”, Bri- tish Journal of Community Justice, Vol. 6 No. 2 April 2008, page 66. 21 Lindsay Arthur, “Tomorrow’s Choices”, Juvenile and Fa- mily Court Journal, Vol. 61 No. 3 July 2010, page 30. 17 80 Jurnal Dinamika Hukum Vol. 15 No. 1, January 2015 Table 8: Limitation of Children Age Dealing with Law in Other Country As a form of Diversion by Prosecutors Before the case is tried Upon request of the public prosecutor or the other Parties For Delays Condemnation by the Court until the Penal Mediation Completed The public prosecutors can refer to penal mediation implementation allows the perpetrator to fix or show his desire to improve his offense to the victim. In this case, the public prosecutor shall not take any action to force abusers as well as meet its stated in the mediation agreement. In this case, the judge will ask mediator of the initial report stated that the case deserves to do mediation. When the mediation has been completed and there has been agreement on a results agreement of mediation, the mediator shall submit a final report to the judge and the judge will consider the results of the mediation decision whether mediation is appropriate decision or need to be sentenced to another. Source: Arthur Closing Conclusion The enactment of Law 11/2012, the SPPA in Indonesia has implemented the concept of restorative justice through versioned. This pro- vision simply accommodate the concept of res- torative justice through diversion system with thrust of things regarding: (a) the obligation to give precedence to the completion of the child through the process of criminal diversion; (b) the duty of every law enforcement agencies to seek diversion at every level examination; and (c) the existence and tasks of professional social workers, social welfare personnel, as well as the community supervisor. As for the diversion pro- cess is done through deliberations involving the child and the parent/guardian, the victim and/ or parent/guardian, the civic, and the super- vising social workers professionals. Deliberation can involve social welfare personnel, and/or the community, in the event it is necessary. Besides Indonesia, many in other countries are first applied the concept of restorative jus- tice through versioned. In General, any other country done diversion for the best interests of the child (the perpetrators) are implemented in the form of mediation. Children are expected to account for his actions without going through the courts. Suggestion Needed the support of the various parties in order to implement the concept of restorative justice through the system are versioned. The support, among others, as follows: Makers of Laws and Regulation Law Enforcement Officers Community To speed up the formation of a go- vernment regulation that governs technically on the implementation process of the diversion, the proce- dures, the implementation and coor- dination of versioned, as mandated in article e15 of ACT 11/2012. In the future, the law enforcement agencies would also have to change the paradigm of retributive to resto- rative in the resolution of criminal cases. In addition, it would also in- crease the capacity and quality of the law enforcement officers throu- gh adequate education and training, in order that the process carried out in accordance with the diversion ap- proach the concept of restorative justice which is ideal. To improve the effectiveness of the imple- mentation of the concept of restorative jus- tice through versioned system then needed an increase in community awareness regar- ding the understanding of children’s rights and the process of diversion. So it can be created in common views and community participation in the protection of the right of the child through the process of diversion. In addition, it takes the cooperation with the community to provide support and accept the criminal perpetrators of the community again. Bibliography Abrams, Douglas. “A Primer on Juvenile Protec- tive Legislation”. Juvenile and Family Court Journal. Vol 65 September 2014; Arthur, Lindsay. “Tomorrow’s Choices”. Juveni- le and Family Court Journal. Vol. 61 No. 3 July 2010; Bazemore, Gordon, Jay Zaslaw, dan Danielle Riester. “Behind the Walls and Beyond: Restorative Justice. Instrumental Commu- nities, and Effective Residential Treat- ment”. Juvenile and Family Court Jour- nal. Vol. 56 No. 1 January 2005; Bazemore, Gordon dan Susan Day. “Restoring the Balance: Juvenile and Community Jus- Criminal Justice System of Children: An Overview Restorative Justice Concept... 81 tice”. Journal of the Office of Juvenile Justice and Deliquency Prevention. Vol. 3 No. 1 March 2010; Becroft, Andrew. “Children and Young People in Conflict With The Law: Asking The Hard Questions”. Juvenile and Family Court Journal. Vol. 57 No. 4 September 2006; Buffington, Kristine Carly Dierkhising, and Shawn Marsh. “Ten Things Every Juvenile Court Should Know About Trauma and Delinquency”. Juvenile and Family Court Journal. Vol. 61 No. 3 August 2010; Coppins, Vanessa, Sharon Casey, dan Allan Cam- pbell. “The Child’s Best Interest: A Review of Australian Juvenile Justice Legisla- tion”. The Open Criminology Journal. Vol. 1 No. 4 August 2011; Hartmann, Arthur.“Victim-Offender-Mediation in Germany”. British Journal of Commu- nity Justice. Vol. 6 No. 2 April 2008; Illinois Criminal Justice Commission. 2012. Poli- cies and Procedures of The Illinois Juve- nile Justice System. Chicago: Illinois Cri- minal Justice Information Authority; Jackson, Shelly, Janet Warren, dan Jessica Jo- nes Coburn. “A Community-Based Model for Remediating Juveniles Adjudicated In- competent to Stand Trial: Feedback from Youth, Attorneys, and Judges”. Juvenile and Family Court Journal. Vol. 65 No. 2 January 2014; Mestitz, Anna. “Organisational Features of Vic- tim-Offender Mediation With Youth Offen- ders In Europe”. British Journal of Com- munity Justice. Vol. 6 No. 2 April 2008; Muncie, John. “International Juvenile (in) Jus- tice: Penal Severity and Rights Complian- ce”. International Journal for Crime, Jus- tice and Social Democracy. Vol. 2 No. 2 July 2013; Olafson, Erna dan Julie Kenniston. “Obtaining Information From Children in The Justice System”. Juvenile and Family Court Jour- nal. Vol. 59 No. 4th November 2008; Pinim, Sufriadi dan Erasmus Napitupulu. 2013. Studi Atas Praktik-Praktik Peradilan Anak di Jakarta. Jakarta: Institure for Criminal Justice Reform; Rosidah, Nikmah. “Pembaharuan Ide Diversi da- lam Implementasi Sistem Peradilan Anak di Indonesia”. Jurnal Masalah-Masalah Hukum. Vol. 41 No. 2 April 2012; Wahwassuck, Korey. “The New Face of Justice: Joint Tribal-State Jurisdiction”. Juvenile and Family Court Journal. Vol. 60 No. 1 December 2009; Yunus, Yutirsa. “Analisis Konsep Restorative Jus- tice Melalui Sistem Diversi Dalam Sistem Peradilan Pidana Anak Di Indonesia”. Jur- nal Rechts Vinding. Vol. 2 No. 2nd August 2013. Jakarta: Pusat Penelitian dan Pe- ngembangan Sistem Hukum Nasional Ba- dan Pembinaan Hukum Nasional; Zagar, Robert John. “Delinquency Best Treat- ments: How to Divert Youths from Violen- ce While Saving Lives and Detention Costs”. Behavioral Sciences & The Law. Vol. 31 No. 3 June 2013; Zulfa, Eva Achjani. “Keadilan Restoratif dan Revitalisasi Lembaga Adat di Indonesia”. Jurnal Kriminologi Indonesia. Vol. 6 No. 2nd August 2010. work_h6a7pftyozeftm2ts7zj2ptxme ---- Rights, Duties and the Separateness of Persons Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=rppa20 Philosophical Papers ISSN: 0556-8641 (Print) 1996-8523 (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rppa20 Introduction: Globalizing or Transcending Global Justice? Uchenna Okeja To cite this article: Uchenna Okeja (2017) Introduction: Globalizing or Transcending Global Justice?, Philosophical Papers, 46:1, 1-11, DOI: 10.1080/05568641.2017.1295615 To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/05568641.2017.1295615 Published online: 21 Mar 2017. Submit your article to this journal Article views: 372 View related articles View Crossmark data Citing articles: 2 View citing articles https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=rppa20 https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rppa20 https://www.tandfonline.com/action/showCitFormats?doi=10.1080/05568641.2017.1295615 https://doi.org/10.1080/05568641.2017.1295615 https://www.tandfonline.com/action/authorSubmission?journalCode=rppa20&show=instructions https://www.tandfonline.com/action/authorSubmission?journalCode=rppa20&show=instructions https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/mlt/10.1080/05568641.2017.1295615 https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/mlt/10.1080/05568641.2017.1295615 http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1080/05568641.2017.1295615&domain=pdf&date_stamp=2017-03-21 http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1080/05568641.2017.1295615&domain=pdf&date_stamp=2017-03-21 https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/citedby/10.1080/05568641.2017.1295615#tabModule https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/citedby/10.1080/05568641.2017.1295615#tabModule Philosophical Papers Vol. 46, No. 1 (March 2017): 1-11 ISSN 0556-8641 print/ISSN 1996-8523 online © 2017 The Editorial Board, Philosophical Papers DOI: 10.1080/05568641.2017.1295615 http://www.tandfonline.com Introduction: Globalizing or Transcending Global Justice?1 Uchenna Okeja Global justice is one of the areas in contemporary political philosophy where one can guarantee almost without error that interesting conferences and new publications will jostle for the attention of scholars every new month. The diversity and widespread interest in this topic notwithstanding, an important issue that is hardly scrutinized is the way the story unfolds. In most cases, the texts on global justice begin with a narrative about how John Rawls classic, A Theory of Justice (1971) and the responses to it, most especially by Charles Beitz and Thomas Pogge, led Rawls to restate his views in another book, The Law of Peoples (1999). The narrative would then continue by making clear that the issue at stake is the contention regarding the possibility of extending Rawls’ notion of distributive justice beyond the context he envisaged—within nations. Depending on the dispositions and perspicacity of the author, the story of global justice then fragments at this point into distinct positions, with some authors professing to be cosmopolitans, others statists and, a few, the faithful proponents of all the in-betweens of the two divide. Understood this way, the idea of global justice would seem to have developed and progressed without any meaningful disjunction, the implication being that the provenance of the field is apparent and settled. In other words, the impression given is that there is an ‘official’ narrative regarding the idea of global justice we can harness when we 1 Over the years, my engagement with the idea of global justice and the broader field of political philosophy has profited from discussions with many colleagues. I thank Philipp Schink, Dorothea Gädeke, Matthias Lutz-Bachmann, Paul Nnodim, Katrin Flikschuh, Ward E. Jones, Anke Graness, Julian Culp and Scott E. Hendrix for sharing their perspectives with me and compelling me to clarify my views. 2 Uchenna Okeja develop syllabi for courses on the topic. This makes it unsurprising to encounter people who wrote their PhD on global justice but have little knowledge beyond Rawls and the fragmented positions emanating from disagreements about his views on the scope of distributive justice. For people culturally and physically outside the context of this ‘settled’ narrative, engaging in the debate on global justice would necessarily invite questions. People interested in the sort of philosophy done outside the space where this settled narrative is embedded will have a hard time making sense of the parochial universalism of this ‘official’ narrative. To this end, a special issue on ‘African philosophy and global justice’ needs contextualization. For anyone aware of developments in the discourse on global justice, it should be clear that very little plurality exists with regard to the theoretical traditions informing the discourse. Comparative studies are few and far between. This leads people interested in African philosophy to query global theorists’ lack of engagement with African philosophy. Put differently, why are people working on African philosophy not visible participants in the discourse on global justice, given especially the trajectory of this tradition of philosophy? One could, of course, hypothesize different reasons to explain the situation. It could be argued, for instance, that this lack of engagement is the result of uncertainty in African philosophy regarding who or what to engage with. Another possible explanation could be that global justice does not address the philosophical concerns of African philosophers. One could also hypothesize that the problem lies in the dearth of relevant resources in African philosophy— essentially, a sort of hermeneutic handicap. In addition, it could be argued that African philosophers are simply not philosophically productive with regard to questions about global justice. Even if one were to accept these explanations as plausible (although they are not, as I will point out anon), that would still not provide a satisfactory answer to the question regarding the little contact between global justice discourse and African philosophy. This is because a tradition of philosophy could be part of a global discourse as a result of Introduction: Globalizing or Transcending Global Justice? 3 its theories being harnessed by philosophers from anterior traditions. Most often, the purpose of engaging with other traditions of thought is to sharpen the inter-contextual validity of propositions—basically an attempt to refine the philosophical propositions we put forward by relating them to contexts other than our own. Western philosophical perspectives have been integrated, for instance, into contemporary philosophical discussions about the nature and scope of freedom in Asian as well as in African philosophy. Thus, it does not suffice to say that the reason African philosophy is ignored in important philosophical debates, such as the one on global justice, is because African philosophers do not actively contribute their perspectives to the discourse. It would of course be desirable for them to do so, but given that African philosophy is a tradition of philosophy accessible to anyone interested, its resources are available to be critically integrated into important debates by philosophers from anterior traditions. There is nothing stopping a theorist of global justice, whose work is embedded in Western philosophy, from engaging with Odera Oruka, Ifeanyi Menkiti, Kwasi Wiredu and other renowned African philosophers. In sum, what I am trying to point out here is that the possible failure of African philosophers to engage with the discourse on global justice does not absolve theorists of global justice from their failure to engage with the resources in African philosophy. Perhaps the whole question regarding the failure to engage with African philosophy in the discourse on global justice is wrong or even perverse. It is surely odd to ask someone who does not speak to you to explain their silence. Certainly, that would only happen if the person is a subordinate. By implication, therefore, it could be argued that it is condescending and futile to inquire into the reasons that account for the silence of African philosophy in the discourse on global justice. I grant that this is an important perspective to consider. However, it seems to me that there is a nexus between the trajectory of African philosophy and the discourse on global justice that should make them natural dialogue partners. And this relates not just to the linguistic proximity of 4 Uchenna Okeja both the practitioners of African philosophy and the prominent theorists of global justice (like majority of the works on global justice, most of the works in African philosophy are in English and French), but, most essentially, to the questions discussed in both contexts of inquiry. Global justice explores the unjust nature of the inequality of the world in which we live. Its central question pertains to how global inequality should be addressed from the perspective of justice. Bruce M. Landesman recounts that global justice asks the following questions: ‘Should we have a more equal world? Should we have a world in which everyone can provide for their basic needs and have their basic rights protected? Should we have a world in which people are roughly equally well off regardless of where they live? Or is the global inequality that now exists, or some ameliorated version of it, morally acceptable and just?’ (Landesman 2011: 421). It should occur to anyone attempting to address these questions that one of the most viable starting points would be to investigate the theories deployed to explain this situation by the agents who bear the brunt of the impacts of the unequal and unjust world at the center of global justice discourse. As Anke Graness (2015: 128) rightly noted, ‘about 20 years before it started to be a central topic in the Euro- American debates of the late 1990s, the Kenyan philosopher Henry Odera Oruka (1944–1995) used the concept of global justice in two key articles, “John Rawls Ideology: Justice as Egalitarian Fairness” (1981) and “The Philosophy of Foreign Aid: A Question of the Right to a Human Minimum” (1989).’ It is worth noting that Oruka’s systematic interest in issues relating to global justice was such that he continued to revise his position. For instance, he updated the perspective he put forward in his paper on ‘The Philosophy of Foreign Aid’ mentioned in the citation above in order to take into account Garett Hardin’s life boat ethics and ‘the concerns of the environmentalists in the 1980’s and 1990’s’ (Oruka 1993: 22–23). Apart from Oruka’s work, there are numerous instances in African political thought that have sought to analyze and critique the unjust arrangement of the world, most especially the unequal power relations that lie at the foundation of the Introduction: Globalizing or Transcending Global Justice? 5 problem of poverty. Kwame Nkrumah, for instance, made the following observation as far back as 1966 ‘Africa is a paradox which illustrates and highlights neo-colonialism. Her earth is rich, yet the products that come from above and below her soil continue to enrich, not Africans predominantly, but groups and individuals who operate to Africa’s impoverishment’ (Nkrumah 1965: 1). He even went on to provide the sort of statistics that we find in the works on global justice discourse— figures that show the dire nature of the poverty, inequality and injustice characteristic of the world in which we live. Yet, the literature on neo- colonialism, the ethical problems related to structural adjustment programs in the third world, dependency theories and liberation philosophy have hardly found their way into mainstream theorization of global justice. Although a special issue on African philosophy and global justice cannot remedy all of the cognitive inaccuracies and moral misperceptions engendered by the neglect of African and other non- Western philosophical traditions in the current discussion of global justice, what it can surely do is to begin the conversation. But to do this, it is essential to highlight some of the reasons that account for the lack of engagement with African philosophy in the mainstream discussion of global justice. To be sure, it is simply not the case, as hypothesized earlier, that there is no clarity in African philosophy regarding who or what to engage with when it comes to the question of global justice. Clarity regarding who or what to engage with emerges when we consider that African philosophy designates a critical and systematic reflection on the fundamental questions of life within the context of African experience. Thus, the concerns of the discipline will necessarily include, among other things, the African experience of the social and material conditions of existence. This means that the resources in African philosophy attempting to make sense of the social, political and material conditions of life are apt to provide penetrating insights into the disadvantage occasioned by the experience of global injustice. Against this background, I do not see the way the initial hypothesis alluded to 6 Uchenna Okeja above will explain the lack of engagement with African philosophy by theorists of global justice. Odera Oruka offers a meaningful explanation of the status quo. He avers that ‘in philosophy, different perspectives can have dialogue only if each of the promoters of one perspective appreciates and respects the seriousness of the perspective of a different person or group’ (Oruka 1990: 36). He explains further that even where this criterion is met, there is still need for a referee ‘to conduct and judge the dialogue.’ Although this role has, up till now, been played by history, ‘many have been reading history wrongly or biasedly. They have read history to find a justification for their perspective and special position. That position can be of a conviction that one is a master or servant’ (Oruka 1990: 36). To solve this problem, Oruka proposed a way out, namely, that we should ‘use history to create a new history’ (Oruka 1990: 36). When we contextualize Oruka’s remarks, it could be argued that the history of Western philosophy is one of the factors precluding theorists of global justice from engaging with non-Western philosophies, such as African philosophy. If one insists on limiting philosophy proper only to the texts whose provenance is traceable in some clear ways to Thales, the proto philosopher, then, for that person, engagement with non-Western philosophy will remain an undesirable illusion. Beyond what Oruka pointed out, however, I am persuaded that there are some important reasons embedded in the contemporary practice of African philosophy that account for the lack of engagement with it in theorizing global justice. As I have argued elsewhere (Okeja 2017), ‘just like many contemporary African novelists who use their African experiences and background as resources for their work but are hardly accessible to their African audience, contemporary African philosophers are mostly not in conversation with one another and their context.’ African philosophers are mostly dislocated today because their works, in most cases, seek to conform and address a non-African audience. One chief reason for this is the guidelines regulating research and career progression in African universities. The corporatized African university Introduction: Globalizing or Transcending Global Justice? 7 today requires that African scholars, philosophers included, must publish in so-called accredited journals with impact. The outcome of this practice is the waning of the internal debate among African philosophers. Without a robust internal debate in a tradition of philosophy, it will be difficult to draw the attention of philosophers working in anterior traditions. Where African philosophers are in conversation, the engagement often whittles down into mutual admiration or suspicion. Compared to what obtained in the discussions among first generation postcolonial African philosophers in journals, such as Second Order and Quest, there is a general lack of robust discussion among contemporary practitioners of African philosophy in the academia. If African philosophy is going to be part of the discourse on global philosophical questions, part of the reason would be that it is a thriving tradition of philosophy. The implication is that African philosophers must be engaged in a robust internal and external discussion. But then, why is it desirable to engage with African philosophy in the discussion of global justice? As noted earlier, global justice attempts to grapple with questions that are reflective of the lived experience of inequality and the global injustice it engenders. Thus, recognition of the agency of the people impacted by this situation should propel a theorist dealing with this dimension of their experience to engage with the perspectives their reflection on the situation offers. Most importantly, however, engagement with African philosophy by theorists of global justice is imperative due to the promise of global philosophy. Thom Brooks puts this point aptly. As an ‘unbounded approach to philosophy’, Brooks avers that global philosophy is motivated by focus on ‘improved ability to address philosophical problem-solving’ (Brooks 2013: 258). It ‘is about our having an openness for the need to pursue wider engagement in order to improve potential argumentative power … [it] is not about speaking to all traditions but rather about speaking with diverse traditions’ (Brooks 2013: 262). In contrast to comparative philosophy, global philosophy does not aim to ‘compare and contrast 8 Uchenna Okeja but to uncover new philosophical insights in order to further develop our own tradition’ (Brooks 261). Notwithstanding the merits of Brooks’ proposals about the benefits of global philosophy, it is essential to underscore that what counts is substantive engagement with diverse traditions in the quest for philosophical understanding of global problems—such as poverty, global justice, identity, terrorism etc. As Leigh Jenco pointed out, engagement with other traditions often highlights the aspects that resonate with ‘Western categories, rendering non-Western ideas, thinkers and traditions interesting as case studies but not themselves the domain of theorizing’ (Jenco 2010:9). This definitely is not a viable approach. A substantive approach is one that pays attention to the contextual dynamics of anterior thought traditions, the goal being to understand, rather than to dismiss or uncritically appropriate. Even with these elucidated points, questions could still be raised about the African philosophy one should engage with, the point being that Africa is ‘big’ and thus entails the existence of a plurality of philosophical perspectives. In effect, the idea is that the diversity of ethnic groups in Africa makes unclear which ‘African’ philosophy one should engage with. Effectively, what is implied is the ‘Africanness’ of African philosophy. Given that this issue has been explored by many African philosophers, the remark I should note in this regard is that this concern is not useful because it is incoherent. And I say so for two reasons. First, it equates African philosophy with ethnic philosophies or worldviews. This is clearly wrong and prejudicial. Secondly, it creates a duty of information for an external other in order to exonerate the powerful ignorance of the subject articulating the position. Since African philosophy designates written and oral texts that are accessible to people, the onus is on the subject of knowledge to inquire further about the insights it offers. Redirecting the discourse on global justice through engagement with other traditions, such as African philosophy, is certainly not a favor to non-Western philosophers. Hamid Dabashi is certainly right to Introduction: Globalizing or Transcending Global Justice? 9 emphasize that many non-Western theorists ‘are no longer interested in whatever it is [European philosophers] fancy to be “hegemonic” or “counter-hegemonic” in Europe and for Europeans’ (Dabashi 2015: 4). The West has become provincialized, hence, its grand narratives about universal philosophical theories, which are all too often parochial, have lost their magic. In global philosophy, it is offered another opportunity to reimagine itself as an equal partner in dialogue without any supercilious pretensions. The essays in this special issue provide substantive engagements with aspects of global justice within the context of African philosophy. Ifeanyi I. Menkiti’s paper titled ‘Africa and Global Justice’ analyzes the ways justice is employed and the complexities involved. He makes clear that it is essential to delimit the scope of justice in order to understand the place of mercy. Aptly, he concludes that ‘for Africans, the choice then remains to join the debate on the peoples’ side of things, not on the states’ side. As peoples, Africans have already attained standing, but as states their grounding is precarious, the battles they are supposed to be fighting ethically suspect.’ Katrin Flikschuh’s paper extends the discussion by exploring the desirability or otherwise of African thinkers’ engagement in the discourse on global justice, given the neglect of their tradition in the mainstream discourse. Her careful analysis shows the dimensions of the parochial universalism of Western philosophy, the formidable challenge it received from African philosophers and the implications of this experience for global justice discourse. Dennis Masaka’s paper discusses the problem of epistemic injustice, the goal being to show that epistemicide is an injustice whose neglect does not conduce to any talk about global justice. He accounts for the link between unequal power relations between the global North and global South and epistemic hegemony. He aims in this regard to show that epistemic parity should be the prolegomena to any viable discussion of global justice. Michael Onyebuchi Eze recalls cosmopolitanism from its wondrous sojourn in the far lands of the world to face a basic challenge—how 10 Uchenna Okeja should we live with the stranger ‘beyond the requirement(s) of the law’? Traversing a range of issues and positions in the discourse on cosmopolitanism, Eze shows that what is at stake is to determine ‘who we can become as ethical beings’. Thaddeus Metz confronts development theory and practice within the context of a carefully formulated theory of an African ethic. Given the idea of communion or communalism characteristic of African mode of being, what are the plausible implications we can infer for the discourse on development? He examines this question in order to point out a viable grounding of ‘social progress’ and ‘what justice demands from the West in relation to Africa.’ Edwin Etieyibo provides an account of a cosmopolitan moral and political theory based on Ubuntu. On the basis of Ubuntu cosmopolitanism, he explored the grounds of the duty and obligations we owe to other human beings. Helen Lauer pursues another important goal in her paper. She deploys the resources of West African social and political practice to show, among other things, that global justice is a process, which means that it is a work in progress. Rhodes University U.Okeja@ru.ac.za References Anke Graness, ‘Is the Debate on “Global Justice” a Global One? Some Considerations in View of Modern Philosophy in Africa,’ Journal of Global Ethics 11: 1 (2015), 126–140. Bruce Landesman, ‘Global Justice’ in: Deen K. Chatterjee (ed.), Encyclopedia of Global Justice (Dordrecht: Springer 2011). Charles Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press 1979). H. Odera Oruka, ‘Parental Earth Ethics,’ Quest: An International African Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 7, 1 (1993), 20–27. Hamid Dabashi, Can Non-Europeans Think? (London: Zed Books 2015). Henry Odera Oruka, ‘Cultural Fundamentals in Philosophy: Obstacles to Introduction: Globalizing or Transcending Global Justice? 11 Philosophical Dialogues,’ Quest: An International African Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 9, 2 (1990), p. 21–37. John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press 1971). John Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1999). Kwame Nkrumah, Neocolonialism: The Last Stage of Imperialism (New York: International Publishers Co. Inc. 1966). Leigh K. Jenco, Making the Political: Founding and Action in the Political Theory of Zhang Shizhao (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2010). Thom Brooks, ‘Philosophy Unbound: The Idea of Global Philosophy,’ Metaphilosophy, Vol 44, 3 (2013), 254–266. Thomas Pogge, Realizing Rawls (Ithaca: Cornel University Press 1989). Uchenna Okeja, Consensus and Palaver as Metaphors for the Public Sphere in: Murad Idris, Leigh Jenco and Megan Thomas (eds), Oxford Handbook of Comparative Political Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press) Forthcoming. work_h7gtb4bebffwtbzligrbvczgxy ---- To imagine and pursue racial justice To imagine and pursue racial justice Matthew Desmonda* and Mustafa Emirbayerb aSociety of Fellows, Harvard University, Cambridge, USA; bDepartment of Sociology, University of Wisconsin, Madison, USA At the conclusion of many courses on race and racism, students, having learned, some for the !rst time, about the existence, origins, and complex dimensions of racial domination in America, are left pondering their next steps. ‘What is to be done?’ many ask. ‘And what, exactly, is it that we want?’ Important as they are, these questions too often are given insuf!- cient attention, usually addressed at the end of the semester, sometimes only on the !nal day of class. And students inquiring about the most effective ways to strive toward racial justice are at a loss to !nd a single comprehensive source that provides them with basic analytical guidance about the goals one should work toward (the ends) or the strategies one should employ to achieve those goals (the means). We believe that stu- dents would bene!t greatly from such a source, and we attempt to offer one here. To effectively address racial domination, we argue, one must have not only an idea of the means with which to struggle on behalf of a reconstructed racial order, but also an idea of the ends for which one is struggling. Accordingly, in the !rst major section of this article, we spec- ify three ends: (1) a society where racial domination is addressed intelli- gently; (2) a society that embraces racial justice in all its arenas; and (3) a society that values and practices multiculturalism – offering a glimpse of what a society without racial domination might look like. In the following section, we specify the means – emphasizing four levels or sites of change having to do with: (1) ourselves; (2) our inner circle; (3) our institutions; and (4) our nation – offering some guidance as to how we each can do our part to bring forth a more racially just society. Although we believe this article will provide guidance for advanced scholars and instructors, we have composed it primarily with a broader audience in mind. Keywords: multiculturalism; racial justice; race politics Personal and civic responsibility No, you weren’t there. You weren’t there when European tradesmen kid- napped families from Africa and shipped them across the ocean, tossing the *Corresponding author. Email: mdesmond@fas.harvard.edu Race Ethnicity and Education Vol. 15, No. 2, March 2012, 259–289 ISSN 1361-3324 print/ISSN 1470-109X online ! 2012 Taylor & Francis http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/13613324.2011.578124 http://www.tandfonline.com D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 dead and sick overboard, to be separated and shackled, branded and beaten and worked. It wasn’t your idea to destroy American Indians’ way of life, to steal their land, to outlaw their religion, to enforce a system of coloniza- tion that brought them to extinction’s cliff-edge. ‘Manifest Destiny’ was not your cry; you did not load your guns and push the people of Mexico back until Texas and California were ours. You had nothing to do with America’s racist citizenship requirements, which tore so many Asian families apart and led to the brutal exploitation of Asian workers. It wasn’t your idea. Blood is not on your hands. It is true: None of us are personally or directly responsible for the wrongs in"icted by – or to – our ancestors. But all of us are responsible for repairing the damage, for cleaning up the mess. Why? Because responsibil- ity is more – so much more – than simply our duty to answer for deeds we ourselves commit. We can distinguish between personal and civic responsi- bility (Arendt 2003). Personal responsibility is connected to things directly asked of you and wrongs you have committed. If you are a student, it is your personal responsibility to attend lectures and complete assignments; if you steal your roommate’s laptop, it is your personal responsibility to return it and make things right. Civic responsibility, on the other hand, is connected to your ability – your power – to change your community and beyond. Whereas personal responsibility has to do with your connection to the problem, civic responsi- bility is about your connection to the solution. If a heavy storm causes a levee to break and "ood waters to come rushing toward your town, you are not personally responsible for the "ood, of course, but you are civically responsible for protecting your town and its citizens. It is not the levee, but the sandbag, that has your name on it. The idea of civic responsibility implies that we have an obligation to people other than ourselves and our close friends and family. It means that we have an obligation to justice; that we are responsible for the dispos- sessed. This fact remains even if we had nothing to do with bringing about their dispossession. But, honestly, how many of us – white and non-white alike – can claim to have nothing to do with the suffering of others? You weren’t there at the beginning, that’s true enough. But, as scholars have shown, accumulation and disaccumulation, privilege and disadvantage, are inseparable (Brown et al. 2003). Where were your shoes, shirt, and under- wear made? Didn’t part of the money you paid at the mall !nd its way into the pockets of those running sweatshops in New York City’s Chinatown or on the Mexican border? Do you clean your apartment with chemicals devel- oped in the poor black communities of the Mississippi Delta? Where does your trash go? Is it dumped on an American Indian Reservation nearby? Do you secure a feeling of safety by backing ‘tough on crime’ politicians, who build more prisons and lengthen mandatory sentences, causing poor blacks and Latinos to bear the brunt of their scourge? Do you wallow only in your 260 M. Desmond and M. Emirbayer D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 own oppression, refusing to reach out to – or even to notice – other people under the hard heel of domination? Do you believe that your pain is great- est, a conviction that only forti!es racial domination by eroding the possibil- ity of interracial and interethnic coalitions and by causing rifts between blacks and Latinos, Chinese and Koreans, poor whites and poor American Indians? Perhaps, when it comes to racial domination, personal and civic responsibility are not so easily divorced. Perhaps our hands are not as clean as we once thought. ‘But I have done nothing!’ you protest. Exactly: You have done nothing. Today, racial domination persists, not only because politicians and business- men exploit racial divisions for their own gain, but because millions of us, busy with our own lives, hunker down in the shade, indifferent to the suffer- ing of others. We might hope for the best, but we refuse to ‘stand in the bright sun and cast a long shadow,’ in civil rights activist Bob Moses’s ele- gant words. As Holocaust survivor Elie Wiesel (1986) once said, ‘The oppo- site of love is not hate; it’s indifference. The opposite of beauty is not ugliness; it’s indifference. The opposite of faith is not heresy; it’s indiffer- ence. And the opposite of life is not death, but indifference between life and death.’ We can drop bombs on civilian targets without being the one who pushes the button. We can incarcerate thousands of black men without sit- ting on the jury. We can contribute to the suffering of America’s immigrants without ever doing the deporting ourselves. Indifference is never neutrality; it is loyalty to the status quo. To quote Lorraine Hansberry, the great African American playwright, ‘The acceptance of our present condition is the only form of extremism that discredits us before our children’ (quoted in Nemiroff 1969, 72). Indifference sometimes is the product of ignorance. Some people simply do not know the nature and depth of the matter. There is a small library’s worth of research to rectify that problem. This article, by contrast, assumes that you have some grasp on racial domination – that you are familiar with its origin and history, how it penetrates various realms of society. Having familiarized yourselves with the problem of racial injustice, what do you do with all this knowledge? What is to be done? And what, exactly, is it that we want? In this article, we address these questions. The !rst section takes up a discussion of ends, some goals toward which we ought to strive. We specify three ends: (1) a society where racial domination is addressed intelli- gently; (2) a society that embraces racial justice in all its arenas; and (3) a society that values and practices multiculturalism – offering a glimpse of what a society without racial domination might look like. The second sec- tion deals with the means or strategies for achieving those goals. We specify four levels or sites of change: (1) ourselves; (2) our inner circle; (3) our institutions; and (4) our nation – and offer some guidance as to how we each can do our part to bring forth a more racially just society. To put it Race Ethnicity and Education 261 D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 another way, the !rst section addresses the question: What is it we wish to achieve? The second addresses the question: And how do we achieve it? The ends Many of America’s whites believe that racial equality already has been achieved, while many of its non-whites hold that little has changed since the Civil Rights Movement and that things may be getting worse (Brown et al. 2003, 224–5). One side declares, ‘Racial harmony has arrived.’ The other side replies, ‘Racial harmony will never come.’ But the truth lies somewhere in the middle. Two things are undeniable: that racial progress in America has been nothing short of astounding and that racial domination in America has yet to be dismantled. As one sociologist has put it, ‘It can be said, unconditionally, that the changes that have taken place in the United States over the past !fty years are unparalleled in the history of minority–majority relations. . . .There does not exist a single case in modern or early history that comes anywhere near the record of America in changing majority atti- tudes, in guaranteeing legal and political rights, and in expanding socioeco- nomic opportunities for its disadvantaged minorities’ (Patterson 1998, 16). If we refuse to recognize this fact, we foster an angry spirit of cynicism and nihilism, a spirit of hopelessness that causes whites and non-whites to throw up their hands and conclude, ‘If racial equality is hopeless, then why should we do anything to !ght it?’ Change has come to America. Indeed, some ethnic con"icts viewed as intractable and eternal a mere 100 years ago hardly exist today. One thinks, for example, of the con"ict between Protestants and Catholics, or between Irish and Italians. The historical record demonstrates that what one genera- tion found unrealistic and impossible – idealistic – the succeeding generation made into reality (Du Bois 1996 [1899], 386). ‘What is considered impossi- ble today may be possible tomorrow,’ observe the authors of White-Washing Race. ‘It is well to remember that in the 1950s few Americans believed that a revolution in civil rights was just around the corner. Jim Crow seemed to be deeply entrenched, racial prejudice too formidable a presence in the minds of white Americans. Yet many people of all races vigorously opposed segregation anyway, not because they knew they would prevail, but because they believed that doing so was morally necessary. And in the end they did prevail’ (Brown et al. 2003, 248). We cannot deny the progress of the past, just as we cannot turn a blind eye to the problems of the present – or the pregnant promise of the future. Researchers and social commentators rightly have documented the (racial) troubles of today, but what does the future hold? What do we want it to hold? Social science is able to provide a much-needed picture of alternative realities. It can, in a phrase, present us with real utopias. Creative and radi- cal alternatives for society ‘grounded in the real potentials of humanity’ as 262 M. Desmond and M. Emirbayer D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 well as in social-scienti!c and historical research, real utopias are intellectu- ally rigorous, carefully designed blueprints for a better tomorrow (Wright 2003, vii–viii; see also Bourdieu 2003, 17–25). They are the end products of social change; they are realistic renderings of a society more just, equal, and moral than the one we currently inhabit. Real utopias are hopeful but not naïve; realistic but not cynical. They are what America’s founding fathers envisioned when they longed for ‘a more perfect union’; what Karl Marx had in mind when he spoke of real or ‘human emancipation’ of the working class; of what Martin Luther King, Jr. dreamt when he referred to ‘the promised land.’ (For an extended discussion of realized real utopias in the political and economic spheres, see Cohen and Rogers 1993; Wright 2010.) To work toward racial justice, we must know precisely what we are working toward. Accordingly, in what follows, we sketch three goals, three real utopias, connected to the dismantling of racial domination. This discus- sion is not a venture in prediction, the stuff of social forecasting; rather, it is an exercise of the imagination. Nor do we paint a complete picture of what a racially just society might look like, a project too rich and expansive for our purposes here. We simply sketch what we believe are three ends essen- tial to the ascension of racial justice, inviting you to !ll in the details and, with us, to imagine further possibilities. Multiculturalism The !rst end we propose is: a society that values and practices multicultur- alism. Multiculturalism – de!ned by German philosopher Jürgen Habermas (2003, 4) as ‘the equal co-existence of different cultural forms of life within one and the same political community’ – is one speci!c way in which peo- ple (especially those belonging to marginalized groups) can be incorporated into society. It breaks sharply with assimilationist logic. ‘Multiculturalism dramatically expands the range of imagined life experiences for core-group members. In doing so, it opens up the possibility not just for acceptance and toleration but for understanding and recognition. Insofar as such understand- ings are achieved, rigid distinctions between core and out-group members break down, and notions of the particular and the universal become much more thoroughly intertwined’ (Alexander 2006, 450–5). In its purest form, multiculturalism abolishes ethnic hierarchies and racial domination. All peo- ple, whites and non-whites, immigrants and native-born citizens, are not simply tolerated; they are valued and, as much as possible, are understood – their differences and similarities acknowledged, accepted, and welcomed. Let us take a moment to ponder multiculturalism, not only as a partly and selectively realized reality (which it is), but also as a real utopia. Much has been written about it, in a vast and exciting literature that spans philoso- phy, political theory, cultural studies, as well as sociology. Here we can only Race Ethnicity and Education 263 D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 offer a few brief ideas. To begin with, in multicultural theory, the ideal America is not one in which all citizens dissolve into a single national iden- tity, an America that would only reproduce the worldviews and lifestyles of the dominant groups. On the contrary, it is a world of multicultural incorpo- ration that rests on two key principles: !rst, that, drawn shoulder to shoulder in common humanity with others, we have a civic responsibility to all peo- ple; and, second, that we must respect each others’ differences (Kymlicka 1995). Anthony Appiah (who prefers the term ‘cosmopolitanism’), puts it this way: There are two strands that intertwine in the notion of cosmopolitanism. One is the idea that we have obligations to others, obligations that stretch beyond those to whom we are related by ties of kith and kind, or even the more for- mal ties of shared citizenship. The other is that we take seriously the value not just of human life but of particular human lives, which means taking an interest in the practices and beliefs that lend them signi!cance. People are dif- ferent, the cosmopolitan knows, and there is much to learn from those differ- ences. Because there are so many human possibilities worth exploring, we neither expect nor desire that every person or every society should converge on a single mode of life. (2006, xv) Multiculturalism promotes the ‘norm of equal inclusion,’ which, in a racially just world, would become a core component of modern democracies (Barry 2001; see also Kymlicka 1995; Habermas 2003). In such a world, there are no ‘second-class citizens,’ and groups currently rendered invisible by political elites !nally receive their due recognition. To Canadian philoso- pher Charles Taylor (1994, 26), failing to recognize fully and to value non- whites and other dominated groups ‘shows not just a lack of due respect. It can in"ict a grievous wound, saddling its victims with a crippling self- hatred. Due recognition is not just a courtesy we owe people. It is a vital human need.’ If one of the primary techniques of those championing racial and colonial domination is to convince those they seek to dominate that whiteness and the ‘white way of life’ are superior to all other races and life- styles, then the aim of the multicultural project is to banish all such ideas of white supremacy and cultural superiority (Fanon 2004 [1963]). Despite our differences – and, indeed, those differences often are far outweighed by our similarities – we all are bound within a common humanity (Phillips 2007; Abu-Lughod 1991). Abraham Lincoln recognized this as far back as the nineteenth century, arguing that immigrants have a right to claim full American citizenship ‘as though they were blood of the blood and "esh of the "esh of the men who wrote the Declaration of Independence. So they are’ (quoted in Alexander 2006, 431). Recognizing this, the multiculturalist cannot deny his or her civic respon- sibility to dominated groups, and it is here that we witness the convergence of anti-racist movements and the multicultural ideal (Banting and Kymlicka 264 M. Desmond and M. Emirbayer D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 2006; Figueroa 1999). Multiculturalism demands that we stand with the suf- fering. It nourishes within us a spirit of solidarity, not only extended to our friends or countrymen, but to every person inhabiting the planet (Alexander 2006; Appiah 2006). The multiculturalist is less interested in protecting exclusively her own group’s agenda – constructing a political identity (based on race, gender, sexual orientation, religion, and so forth) and striving to promote only the aims of those with a similar identity – as much as in imagining and !ghting for a society in which all groups’ needs are realized to the fullest extent possible. In multiculturalism, one !nds a set of moral principles that can replace those of ‘identity politics,’ principles that counter the possibility of interracial and interethnic cooperation (see Brubaker and Cooper 2000; Gitlin 1996). Multiculturalism, after all, is not simply about recognizing other people’s identities and cultural scripts; it is also about rec- ognizing their problems – how they are unfairly treated in a democracy that promises them full and equal inclusion – and about responding with intelli- gent and just remedies (cf. Ford 2005; Phillips 2007). For the multicultural- ist, racial justice is the value; racial diversity and equality are the results. ‘But,’ the cynic interjects, ‘wouldn’t multiculturalism erode our national culture, undermining American unity and pulling us apart?’ Obsessing over our differences, it is true, weakens our democratic potential and breeds ani- mosity. But any multiculturalism worthy of its name does not encourage us to obsess over our differences but inspires us to acknowledge and respect those differences as potential sources of wisdom and good while working together to bring about a more just world. Multiculturalism seeks to draw us nearer, not to push us apart. It does not threaten civic community but nour- ishes its potential by dismantling racial domination (Banting and Kymlicka 2006, 11, 17). It does not weaken democracy but strengthens it. Most critics of multiculturalism believe its alternative to be a color-blind society, where we shed our differences and unite under the banner of ‘American.’ This train of thought is nothing more than the old idea of assimilation in new garb. It assumes that the stew simmering in the great American melting pot suits everybody’s tastes. It also assumes that assimilation melts everyone equally into a new something, even if, in reality, that ‘new something’ is the dominant group projecting itself as the universal American. Whites do not melt; non-whites do. This means that the alternative to multiculturalism is not national unity but disunity and racial strife. Multiculturalism seeks to nourish democracy, to strengthen American civil society, making it freer and fuller, wider and warmer, more inclusive and more just. Besides, to deny the goal of multiculturalism is to deny the very essence of America. America always has been multicultural, although it is only in recent years that it has pursued multiculturalism as an ideal. The United States, said Senator Carl Schurz in 1859, was ‘a great colony of free humanity which has not old England but the world for its mother coun- try’ (Fuchs 1992, 45). It took an enormous labor to convince us otherwise; Race Ethnicity and Education 265 D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 it took a movement of great exertion and coercion, mysti!cation and trick- ery to present America as a white nation. In America, multiculturalism is the norm; it is racial domination that is its perverse, unnatural substitute – which is why Appiah makes perfect sense when he says, ‘Cosmopolitanism isn’t hard work; repudiating it is’ (Appiah 2006, xx). Justice The second end we propose is: a society that embraces racial justice. Because racial domination has been such a central feature of American soci- ety since its inception, it might be dif!cult to imagine an America where racial justice !nally has come to replace injustice. Some people have given up trying (Bell 1987). But there is no surer way to guarantee racial domina- tion’s continued reign than to conceive of it as intractable and eternal. Imag- ining alternatives to how we should live is itself a small act of resistance, one that refuses to settle for the world we have inherited and that !rmly rejects the defeatist claim, ‘This is how it is, and how it has always been, so get used to it.’ Since the collapse of the Civil Rights Movement, most activists in Amer- ica simply have not known where to march next (Winant 2001). During Jim Crow, racial domination was obvious and legal; there was a clear enemy (segregation) and a clear goal (desegregation). But today, racial domination can be more elusive and complicated; it can be ghostlike and dif!cult to confront. There is a good deal of truth to this, but numerous studies (Wes- tern 2006; Brown et al. 2003; Feagin, Vera, and Batur 2001; Bonilla-Silva 2003; Gotanda 2000) have shown that today racial domination in"uences all of society’s !elds of life; its consequences are devastating and, in many cases, its presence undeniable. There are tangible problems in need of tangi- ble solutions. A revitalized Civil Rights Movement – uncompromisingly egalitarian, intersectional, and multicultural – is needed. In the paragraphs below, we offer some direction to that movement, ends it can pursue and, in some cases, is pursing today. What might a racially just America look like? It would take several books, in reality, to answer this question thoroughly. But, in what follows, we imagine some real utopias for several major areas or !elds of social life (proceeding from the macro to the micro), in an exer- cise intended to pry open our imaginations and to stretch the limits of what we believe to be possible. In the political !eld, racial justice would come with the advent of a more powerful multicultural democracy, one that lives up to its name (literally, ‘the rule of the people’) (Hacker and Pierson 2005). Because there is no genuine democracy in societies that muzzle dissenting voices, the new American democracy would value and welcome criticism and would pro- mote (not erode) people’s political freedom. Patriotism would be measured by the extent to which we critically evaluate our society and strive to 266 M. Desmond and M. Emirbayer D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 change things for the better – not the extent to which we nod ‘yes’ to every- thing party of!cials say. Current systems of ‘taxation without representation’ would come to an end, as poor communities of color, as well as ex-felons, would enjoy political representation that matches that of wealthy white sub- urbanites. How, after all, can we accept a society in which ‘the fullness of freedom [is reserved] for those whose income, leisure, and security need no enhancing, and a mere pittance of liberty [is reserved] for the people, who may in vain attempt to make use of their democratic rights to gain shelter from the [powerful]’ (Polanyi 2001 [1944], 265)? In a racially just society, democracy would triumph over oligarchy, and substantive racial representa- tion to political posts would best super!cial representation. Appointed of!- cials would be intimately connected to the needs and problems of all citizens, including those living in disadvantaged non-white communities. This might require abandoning America’s two-party system – the only one of its kind in the democratic world – for a political system where one does not have to choose between Democrats and Republicans. It would most cer- tainly require the revitalization of a powerful and multicultural Civil Rights Movement (Smith 1999). Racial justice in the economic !eld would mean, !rst, the complete and total eradication of racialized poverty. ‘Impossible,’ whispers the cynic. But why? In a racially just society, the gap between the rich and the poor would narrow, as would income and wealth disparities across race. The simulta- neous extraction of immigrant labor and retraction of immigrant rights would cease. America would develop fair policies that treat its poor immi- grants as more than simply an expendable and cheap labor force. And America would help countries such as Mexico revitalize their economy and reduce their poverty, instead of treating those countries as staging grounds where companies can relocate their factories and pay workers a substandard wage. Finally, the skimpy American welfare state – in large part responsible for the millions of citizens living hand-to-mouth today (Wacquant 2007) – would expand by generous proportions, such that ‘the primary obligation of the state’ would be to ‘use its powers and allocate its resources to eradicate poverty and hunger and to assure security of livelihood, security against the major hazards and vicissitudes of life, and the security of decent homes’ (Harvey 2005, 183). The new American welfare state would guarantee peo- ple a livable wage, affordable housing, health care for all, and secure retire- ment plans. There is good reason to believe that racialized poverty could be considerably reduced if poor communities of color were offered a New Deal and Fair Deal comparable to the one offered whites before and after World War II (Katznelson 2005). A residential !eld guided by racial justice would not be scarred by dras- tic segregation but would promote racial integration and multicultural com- munity. More important, it would eliminate the problems associated with racial segregation, problems such as chronic poverty, educational inequality, Race Ethnicity and Education 267 D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 and imbalanced political representation. The American state would initiate massive investment in the nation’s poorest communities and would nourish and promote self-development and sustainable economic growth on Ameri- can Indian reservations. Those living in more af"uent areas would use their af"uence to help others in need instead of building higher fences. Housing discrimination would be shut down. And we would develop cleaner and more energy-ef!cient ways to live, so as not to burden poor and non-white communities with our trash and pollution. One of the most racially unjust institutions today is the American crimi- nal justice system. While non-whites have made gains in the economic and educational !elds in the past 20 years, they have lost ground in the legal realm, as evidenced by the gross racial discrepancies in our prison popula- tion. In a racially just society, those discrepancies would disappear, as would all forms of racial pro!ling as well as the pervasive spirit of racialized fear that links blackness to criminality and Arabness to terrorism. If ‘tough on crime’ policies have not made us safer, as the evidence suggests, then we would abandon those policies in favor of more effective and cost-ef!cient ones. We must think beyond the prison walls, developing alternatives to incarceration that not only decrease racial inequality in punishment but also, unlike our current program of mass incarceration, actually work to decrease crime. A racially just society would mount a proactive assault on the root causes of criminal behavior, instead of relying singularly on reactive pro- grams of harsh punishment. The result would be a safer America – where cities no longer have ‘streets you shouldn’t drive down’ or ‘bad areas of town’ – as well as an expansion of freedom in poor non-white communities previously subjected to drastic policing measures. With respect to education, making higher education more affordable would open up opportunities for thousands of people, including many peo- ple of color, who currently are excluded from the privileges many others enjoy. What is more, a racially just society would invest in its poor schools; and a racially just society would critically reconstruct its curriculum, replac- ing Eurocentric accounts of history, art, politics, and philosophy with a more accurate, well-rounded, and multicultural program of studies (Apple 1999; Banks 2002). In the same vein, the racist aesthetic would be swept out of the aesthetic sphere by an artistic revolution led by non-white and white artists alike, who would renounce caricatured and stereotypical depictions of people of color, as well as distorted and uncomplicated renderings of racism. In their own work, artists would represent people of color in their full humanity, escaping the racist gaze and pushing forward our critiques of racial domina- tion much farther than they have been pushed before. Art of this nature, art upholding an anti-racist aesthetic, would be richly rewarded. In a racially just society, our associations would be guided, not by the principle of homophily, but by an ethic of multiculturalism. Through our 268 M. Desmond and M. Emirbayer D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 associations, we would breach racial and ethnic boundaries instead of reify- ing them. Hate groups would be a thing of the past; and the Internet would become a conduit through which radical multicultural democracy "ourishes and expands its reach. Religious associations would "ourish as institutions of justice and equality and would work to foster a spirit of civic responsibil- ity and mutual connectedness. More broadly, a racially just society would entail the galvanization of civil society, where citizens would be involved and deeply invested in community affairs, voting and participating more fully in the political process and working together to !ght racial injustice and strengthen non-white communities that, for decades, have been over- looked by political elites. Finally, in the intimate !eld, a racially just society would disallow stig- mas from being attached to interracial marriages. All consenting adults would be free to marry whomsoever they chose, unbound by family and community prejudices or by unjust laws. Aggressive programs would be developed to help single mothers and to abolish the feminization of poverty. The majority of citizens would enthusiastically embrace the concept of ‘doing the (racial) work,’ the cultural labor required to transverse ethnic and racial boundaries, the determined broadening of one’s cultural competence in an attempt to adopt, as sincerely as possible, another perspective on the world. Citizens would cultivate their intercultural competence and their desire to understand the world through multiple perspectives, admitting that, on some occasions, their vision of the world may be neither universal nor correct. As a result, everyday interactions between blacks and Jews, Jews and Muslims, Latinos and whites, whites and American Indians, American Indians and Asians, and so forth, would be de!ned, not by anxiety, anger, or fear, but by mutual respect and kindness. Whites would deny their white privilege and use the advantages granted them by racial domination to work on behalf of racial justice. Rejecting feelings of superiority as well as white guilt, both of which sti"e positive action, they would embrace a healthy white identity. Non-whites would abandon any form of ethnic chauvinism and would evict from their thinking all traces of internalized white suprem- acy. All these ends, these real utopian possibilities, are distant, to be sure, but they are not beyond our collective reach. Like the !rst "owers of spring after a long hard winter, changes promoting racial justice already are sprout- ing up all across the nation. The stigma around interracial marriage has been weakened; some American Indian Nations successfully have pulled them- selves out of destitution; the Alternatives to Incarceration Movement has developed many practical forms of punishment that take place beyond the prison cell; chronic poverty has declined by sizeable margins over the last century. We still have a long row to hoe, but the work has already begun – and, already, we have started to reap some fruits of the harvest. You might agree with some of our ideas and disagree with others. And, indeed, we Race Ethnicity and Education 269 D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 have only scratched the surface of the matter. But one point is undeniable: We must never become numb to the now; we must never allow ourselves to be lulled into mistaking the present for the permanent; we cannot permit our minds to be closed to the real possibilities tomorrow offers. We can – and must – do better. Intelligence The third end we propose is: a society where racial domination is addressed intelligently. We use the term ‘intelligence’ deliberately, for what is called for is precisely an application of intelligence in the philosophic sense of that term. To philosophers, intelligence has to do with one’s ability to exercise good judgment in a world full of uncertainty. As John Dewey wrote in The Quest for Certainty, a person ‘is intelligent. . . in virtue of his capacity to estimate the possibilities of a situation and to act in accordance with his esti- mate’ (Dewey 1988 [1929], 170). For Dewey, our ability to solve the prob- lems we confront was directly connected to our ability accurately to assess those problems and to develop different courses of action. American sociol- ogist Charles Horton Cooley, a contemporary of Dewey, concurred that ‘the test of intelligence is the power to act successfully in new situations. We judge a man to be intelligent when we see that in going through the world he is not guided merely by routine or second-hand ideas, but that when he meets a fresh dif!culty he thinks out a fresh line of action appropriate to it, which is justi!ed by its success. . . . It is, then, essentially a kind of fore- sight, a mental reaction that anticipates the operation of the forces at work and is prepared in advance to adjust itself to them’ (Cooley 1966 [1918], 351). Racial domination, like all forms of domination, relies on a tangled col- lection of distortions, illogic, and lies sometimes misrecognized as truth. Logic, rational decision-making, and good sense – the execution of a racial intelligence – can shine a revealing light on the obfuscation linked to racial domination; it can lay bare the true nature of the beast. Racial intelligence can promote a political climate where people desire – need – to know the best and latest information on the pressing problems of the day; and it can lead to successful resolution of those problems. We imagine an opening of the American mind, where ideas and science are treated seriously and with respect and where people realize the power of clear thinking. As Kurt Lewin remarked over 50 years ago, ‘Nothing is more practical than a good theory’ (Lewin 1951, 169). Freedom and knowledge, that is, liberation and rational awareness, are welded together. One cannot exist without the other. C. Wright Mills wrote: Freedom is not merely the chance to do as one pleases; neither is it merely the opportunity to choose between set alternatives. Freedom is, !rst of all, the 270 M. Desmond and M. Emirbayer D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 chance to formulate the available choices, to argue over them – and then, the opportunity to choose. That is why freedom cannot exist without an enlarged role of human reason in human affairs. . . The social task of reason [therefore] is to formulate choices, to enlarge the scope of human decisions in the making of history. (1959, 174) Freedom, in a word, goes hand in hand with intelligence, the ability to spread wide your horizon of possibilities and to make sound judgments in respect of them. In a society such as ours, so !lled with misleading language and technol- ogies of mysti!cation, acting intelligently – that is, actively seeking truth rather than passively accepting this or that party line – is itself a powerful political act. Mills knew this well. Not only did he seek, as a public sociolo- gist, to foster critical thinking in the American citizenry as a whole, but he also noted, with respect to more specialized research, that the very enterprise of social science, as it determines fact, takes on political meaning. In a world of widely communicated nonsense, any statement of fact is of political and moral signi!cance. All social scientists, by the fact of their existence, are involved in the struggle between enlightenment and obscuran- tism. In such a world as ours, to practice social science is, !rst of all, to prac- tice the politics of truth. (Mills 1959, 178) ‘The politics of truth?’ mocks the cynic. ‘What is truth?’ Too often, wherever the question, ‘What is truth?,’ or, more brashly, the declaration, ‘There is no truth!,’ is uttered, indifference, the washing of one’s hands of the problem, is nearby. If there is no right or wrong answer, so the logic goes, then there is no right or wrong action. Is there no better recipe for indifference? The notion that all truth is relative and forever beyond our reach is thoroughly misguided and ought to be discarded. Besides, those who apply such reasoning to the social world would not dare do so to the natural one. The world remains round whether or not you think it so. Reducing hard-earned facts to ‘mere words’ or ‘relative truths’ is a trav- esty and an affront to struggles on behalf of racial justice. There is a differ- ence between opinion and truth. The latter is those opinions that have been subjected to what Dewey called ‘the test of consequences,’ assertions that have been examined and tested and determined collectively and systemati- cally to have warrant (Dewey 1988 [1920], 171, 169). Not all opinions are equal; some are quite wrong and ought to be labeled as such. A black working-class man might perceive that Mexican immigrants are ‘stealing his job,’ but that, according to the best available evidence, would be wrong (Borjas and Tienda 1987; Borjas 1990). The evidence also leads us to con- clude, contrary to popular belief, that white men have not been harmed by af!rmative action (Norton 1996; Jackson 1996; Morin 1997; Reskin 1998) and that the prison boom has not led to a decrease in violent crime (Western Race Ethnicity and Education 271 D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 2006, 185). If we believe otherwise, we ought to be corrected. Opinions should be submitted to the best available evidence. A society of racial intelligence would look quite different from the one we have today, in the domains both of everyday life and of high-level poli- cymaking. In everyday life, citizens would, as a matter of disposition, approach problems and con"icts not in terms of their received prejudices and opinions but in a more open-ended, experimentalist spirit, setting alter- native proposed solutions to the pragmatic test and seeing what works and what doesn’t in furthering a more just and harmonious experience. In high- level policymaking, our politicians would have the best data at their disposal and, crucially, would want to be better informed. Political rhetoric would not be chock full of coded language, buzzwords, and manipulations; the days of the political spokesperson adept at dodging questions and masking truth would come to an end. What is more, instead of making it dif!cult for Americans to know what they are up to, politicians would encourage transparency and openness. We are envisioning a society in which all citizens – from teachers and engineers to domestic workers and truck drivers – would be informed and educated. They would participate in a politics of reason, where their opinions would be tempered by intelligence and the cool-headed evaluation of the best avail- able information. And they would possess a ‘radical doubt,’ a skepticism, sharpened by the scienti!c enterprise, which would help them better to dis- tinguish truth from falsehood (Mullings 2005; Feagin and Vera 2001; Willett 2001). The means Like a great locomotive, the movement toward racial equality and justice began slowly and with considerable effort. But it gained speed with every turn of the wheel and every grate on the track and, soon, it shook the rust off its gears and !red up the engine, and got to rolling. It lumbered forward with great momentum and power and quite literally changed the world. But, since the late 1960s, the movement seems to have lost steam, even in a time when the tenets of anti-racism have grown more widely accepted. Today we !nd ourselves in a unique historical moment. On the one hand, there has never been a time in American history when so many people reject racism. A mere generation ago, racial segregation was the law of the land and was embraced by millions; today, nothing could seem more anti- American. On the other hand, while racial domination continues to cause a great deal of suffering and makes a mockery of our democracy, many move- ments for racial justice have faded away. Never has the value of racial equality been so strong while the movement for racial justice is so weak (Winant 2001). 272 M. Desmond and M. Emirbayer D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 Right now, there are thousands of people working in the name of multi- culturalism and racial liberation. They are running for local of!ce, teaching on reservation schools, giving water to dehydrated border crossers, arguing civil rights lawsuits, and organizing on college campuses and in inner-city neighborhoods and small towns. Of course, on the opposite side of the con- tinuum, there are also thousands of people working on behalf of racial dom- ination. Not just members of hate groups, but business owners who discriminate against black applicants, real estate agents who only show Puerto Rican families homes in poor areas of town, movie producers who encourage distorted depictions of Native Americans, and politicians who turn a blind eye to the pressing problems of racial domination. And in the middle are the hordes of the indifferent. Where do you stand? ‘I cannot change things,’ you say. In fact, it is the other way around: You cannot but help change things. By virtue of existing, we change things. We affect people in our classes, dormitories, jobs, fami- lies, and social clubs, even if we cannot fully realize exactly how. It is not a question of if we will change things but how we will – for the better or for the worse. What is needed is not just an impassioned response to racial injustice but an intelligent response as well. ‘We are not in danger of being excessively generous; indeed, most of us are in no danger of meeting. . . our basic obli- gation. But what’s wanted. . . is the exercise of reason, not just explosions of feelings’ (Appiah 2006, 170). Where, then, do we start? In what follows we explore four levels or sites of change having to do with our (1) selves; (2) inner circle; (3) institutions; and (4) nation. These are not stages one proceeds through so much as overlapping areas of struggle. All are impor- tant; all are integral elements in the search for positive change in racial life. One cannot simply choose among them. The intelligent reconstruction of our racial order requires them all, in combination and in creative synthesis. Self Leo Tolstoy, perhaps Russia’s greatest novelist, once wrote, ‘Everyone thinks of changing the world, but no one thinks of changing himself.’ But this is precisely where we must begin. How, after all, could someone claim to be an environmentalist while refusing to conserve water or to recycle? How could someone claim to be a feminist while mistreating the women in his own life? How could any of us claim to be !ghting for racial justice without yet critically examining our own prejudices? If we want to help dismantle racial domination, we must !rst address it within ourselves. The goal here is not to purify ourselves of all traces of interpersonal racism before getting involved with anti-racist movements. If it were, nothing would ever get done, for, if we are honest with ourselves, most of us have prejudices that cling, barnacle-like, to our thoughts and feelings. The goal is Race Ethnicity and Education 273 D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 not perfection but critical self-engagement, not complete puri!cation (an impossibility) but rigorous re"exivity. Interracial and intercultural competence, moreover, is not a state at which we arrive or something we achieve. It is not a destination but a process, a way of living. There is no conversion moment, no glorious awakening, where once and for all we come out of the darkness and into the light. There is only a life lived, striving and working, succeeding and failing, moving from light to dark and back again. The apt metaphor here is one of training, where day after day we discipline our thoughts and actions so they are not dictated without our consent by forces of domination. This self-training requires, foremost, identifying our prejudices and attempting to scrutinize and, as much as possible, evict them. We must pay serious attention to our thoughts and actions, evaluating how we treat people differently because of their racial identity or how we feel about this or that ‘kind’ of person. Knowing ourselves means taking a good hard look in the mirror and being as honest as a re"ection about what we see. Many of us are truthful with ourselves far too rarely, and, oftentimes, we can practice a kind of disingenuous re!exivity that errs in two opposite directions. On the one hand, we can search within ourselves and happily report that we are free of all prejudices. ‘I treat everyone the same,’ we might declare. ‘I do not have a racist bone in my body.’ On the other hand, we can claim, after a thorough inward-looking meditation, that we are wretches, full of only pre- judice: ‘I am so completely racist; I am helpless.’ One kind of dishonest exaggeration looks inside and !nds an angel, seemingly immune to racial domination; the other !nds a demon that welcomes racial domination with- out resistance. But the truth is that we are all made up of a complicated blend of good and evil, courage and cowardice, ignorance and intelligence. Honest re"exivity confronts the self in its full complexity, and it does not shy away from the nasty bits but seeks them out in order to set them straight. ‘We only become what we are by radically negating deep down what others have done to us’ (Sartre 2004 [1963], li). Our thoughts are ours; we must take responsibility for them. But having a racist thought does not make you a bad person or a ‘racist.’ It makes you a person who has been in"uenced by a society up to its neck in racial domi- nation. You might feel ashamed when a racist thought trespasses your mind, but if shame is your only reaction, you have little chance of controlling your prejudices. ‘Rolling in the muck is not the best way of getting clean’ (Huxley 1998 [1932], vii). To restrain our unconscious racism, we must objectify it and subject it to a historically informed analysis and critique. This endeavor, a sort of socio-analysis that complements and perhaps even goes further than psychoanalysis, is a re"exive enterprise, in which we objectify all those forces that control our imaginations and actions in order rationally to assess and control how they affect our thinking and behavior. We must never stop asking ourselves: Is my idea correct? From where does 274 M. Desmond and M. Emirbayer D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 my information come? How do I know that this is the truth? How is it that I know the world works in this way? How might my upbringing and racial identity in"uence my thinking on this matter? Racial intelligence also requires that we become good listeners, that we ‘pay attention – to others and to the world around [us]’; that we take note of human achievements in art, music, craftsmanship, poetry, politics, sports, literature, and journalism. It requires that we read and that we learn how to communicate our ideas more clearly to others. If we hope to become people of intelligence, driven by a love of learning and a deep commitment to the truth, we must discipline our minds and reject half-baked, sloppy thinking. We must also invest in others’ passions and ideas and ‘understand the power of other people’s dreams and nightmares as well as [our] own.’ We must acknowledge that ‘freedom of the individual is possible only in a free com- munity, and vice versa,’ and therefore understand that our livelihood is inex- orably connected to livelihoods of others (Cronon 1998, 76–8). And we must surround ourselves with people who are different than ourselves, who disagree with us, and who can push and challenge our thinking. In a multi- cultural vein, we should never fear differences or ‘strangeness.’ Rather, we should seek them out, knowing full well that our ‘little shard of mirror can- not re"ect the whole’ (Appiah 2006, 8). Perhaps above all, we must develop empathy. You might be the smartest mind of your generation, able to analyze racial domination with precision and brilliance, but if your stomach does not turn when you hear about a hate crime that happened on your campus or when a friend cracks a racist joke or when you pick up the newspaper and read about America’s growing anti- immigrant sentiment, then your intelligence is in vain (Feagin et al. 2001). The philosopher Hannah Arendt (1978, 104) put it this way: We ‘do not become just by knowing what is just but by loving justice.’ Changing our- selves into agents of change, therefore, means changing our minds by culti- vating knowledge and changing our hearts by cultivating empathy. One kind of change drives the other. The more you learn about racial injustice, the more your heart will break for its victims; likewise, the stronger your pas- sion for justice grows, the more you will want to learn about racial domina- tion and the more you will seek out the best prescriptions for change (Pedersen, Walker, and Wise 2005; Stephen and Finlay 1999). A good deal of this work, this self-work, is carried out in solitude. By ourselves, we read and think in the library; we ponder our own thoughts while walking down the street; we imagine a better world while riding the bus. But this can only take us so far, for re"exivity is a fundamentally collec- tive enterprise. We cannot fully change ourselves by ourselves. For our short- comings to be brought most fully to light, we need to participate in collective dialogues that cut across racial boundaries. The importance of honest discus- sions that grapple with the complexities of racial domination – and especially of conversations that take place between women and men of different racial Race Ethnicity and Education 275 D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 identities – cannot be overstated. As you might already have discovered, talk- ing about race can be painful. Fear and anger, stubbornness and sel!shness can choke rational dialogue and get in the way of progress. What is needed is cool-headedness, humility, and respect; in certain instances, what is needed most might be honest contrition; in others, forgiveness (Patterson 1998; Tatum 1997). Weariness and apathy, too, are signi!cant barriers to engaging in these – often exhausting, often maddening – conversations. ‘I am tired of talking about race,’ you might say. ‘Let’s just put it all behind us.’ Most of the time, white students are the ones who voice this complaint, a complaint that itself is a product of white privilege (Rich and Cargile 2004). Non-whites, whose livelihood, and whose children’s livelihood, depends on overcoming racial domination, do not have much choice in the matter; their weariness comes, not from conversations about racial domination, but from the thing itself. It goes without saying that all of us, whites and non-whites alike, need to carry out this self-work, confronting the many ways in which racial domi- nation is alive in our innermost beings, our unconscious habits, dispositions, and postures. Whites need to come face to face with their racial privilege. They need to interrogate how their thinking is informed by racial domina- tion; they need to reject notions of rugged individuality, which encourages them to ignore the power of history and society (Katz 1978). Non-whites, too, need to confront their own prejudices as well as to turn away from all whispers of self-hate and embrace a positive image of their self in a society that day after day projects negative ones. They need to come to the full real- ization that racial inequalities are the product of racial domination, not of the de!ciencies of non-whites, and must struggle against reproducing the terms of their own domination (Bell 1987, 228–9). And all of us must strive to understand the world through multiple perspectives. Inner circle Racial domination has to be eradicated, not only from our ideas and prac- tices, but also from the ideas and practices of those nearest us – the persons in our intimate circle. You can have great in"uence over how your family members and friends think about the world. How can you address their rac- ism? Every situation is different and requires a good deal of thought, strat- egy, and patience on your part. But if there is a single guiding principle for addressing racism in the lives of people closest to you, it is this: Hold them accountable for their words and deeds – and ask them to do the same to you. A father sees a group of Mexican-American men and observes, ‘All these Mexicans. They are taking our jobs away!’ Knowing he is misinformed, his son responds, with genuine interest, ‘Why do you think that?’ The father 276 M. Desmond and M. Emirbayer D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 replies, ‘It’s just obvious, isn’t it? I mean, you know Bob Kapatrick down the street, he lost his job last year.’ The son answers, ‘That really is sad about Mr Kapatrick, but are you sure he lost his job because of Mexicans? I mean, couldn’t there be other factors involved? I read in the paper that a lot of workers from that factory were laid off, including Mexican workers. You know, I used to think that Mexican immigrants took jobs away from Ameri- cans, but I’ve been convinced otherwise. I started reading up on it, and the best evidence out there shows that Mexican immigrants don’t take jobs away from native-born citizens. They mainly compete for jobs with other immigrants. What do you think?’ When people with racist beliefs are faced with an alternative interpreta- tion about how the world works, a more intelligent interpretation informed by social science, they have a dif!cult time justifying their beliefs. In time, they may come to change their minds and embrace a more informed (and anti-racist) understanding of society. But people often grow defensive and uncomfortable when asked to justify their ideas. Accordingly, there are at least four useful techniques for holding people accountable for their preju- dices. First, take their prejudices seriously. Do not yell at them; do not call them ‘stupid’ or ‘ignorant’; try not to get too angry. If you blow up on peo- ple every time they say something racist, you will not teach them to think differently; you will only teach them not to say such things around you. When confronted with a racist statement – or, more softly, a benign yet mis- informed statement about racial domination – realize that the person who uttered the statement matters very much, that their ideas matter very much, and that their beliefs most likely are tied to their personal experience. If you want them to listen to you, then you must listen – sincerely – to them. Second, ask people questions. In the above conversation, the son responded to his father’s remark with a question and inserted questions throughout the conversation. If he had responded with a statement such as ‘You’re wrong!’ or ‘How can you believe such garbage!’ or ‘You’re so rac- ist!’ he might have blown the teaching opportunity. Questions – posed authentically, not sarcastically or presumptuously – are disarming and invit- ing. They’re also quite natural. If someone says, ‘I think the Los Angeles Lakers are the best basketball team in the country,’ the natural response is to ask, ‘Why?’ Similarly, if someone says, ‘I don’t think American Indians want to climb out of poverty,’ it is equally natural to ask, ‘Why?’ Questions, at bottom, are pursuers of the truth. As such, they are powerful weapons against racist beliefs (Kivel 2002 [1997], 113–14). Third, do your homework. How can you hope to change someone’s mind if you can’t offer them a better interpretation than the one they currently hold? The son was able to offer his father a different way of understanding how Mexican immigrants affect the labor pool because he had read up on the issue. Racial domination’s arch-nemesis is a critically informed citizen. This does not mean you have to memorize statistics (although it’s good to Race Ethnicity and Education 277 D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 store a few in your arsenal) or be able to recite the precise date that marked the beginning of the prison boom. But it does require you to have a grasp of the relevant research !rm enough to allow you to articulate educated positions on certain matters. If your knowledge is a bit shaky, don’t be afraid to tell your family members or friends that you’ll hit the books and get back to them – and be sure you do. Finally, the worst thing you can do upon being confronted with a racist belief – other than remaining silent – is to turn the conversation into a debate you intend to ‘win.’ It is extremely dif!cult to learn when you are competing. After all, in a debate you are not trying to understand; you are trying to beat your opponent. And it is an extremely rare thing for someone to walk away from a debate having learned anything. In most cases, both winners and losers leave the debate thinking one thing: that the other person is an idiot. You should be !rm in your convictions, determined with your questions, and con!dent in your knowledge, but the goal should be a rational discussion, not a debate in the sense of a verbal sparring match. If you set out to intimidate someone or make them feel stupid, you usually will produce in them the desired effect, losing credibility and perhaps even calcifying their racist or wrongheaded beliefs. If you truly want to change someone’s mind, then you have to be willing to be vulnerable and (if appro- priate) honest about your own prejudices. One last thing: think about the timing of your conversation. Sometimes a racist utterance is best addressed on the spot; other times, it is better to confront the person at a later time. Be prepared for resistance, and gird yourself for the long haul. It will take much more than a single conversation adequately to address your friends’ and family members’ interpersonal racism. This – it bears repeating – is a process, not a conversion. Understand, too, that, despite your best efforts, you will not always be successful. Some people will go to their graves with their racism. After trying and trying, sometimes the only thing left to do is to move on, expending your energies elsewhere, like !ghting for racial justice at the institutional level. Institutions Racial domination must be confronted at the interpersonal and institutional levels. There are two kinds of change-oriented institutional action: individual and collective. Individual action involves conducting ourselves in a certain manner within the institutions to which we belong so as to promote racial justice. For example, all of us, no matter what our chosen profession, can promote racial justice within our workplaces. Are you a police of!cer? You can decry the pervasive practice of racial pro!ling, never employing this unfair technique and criticizing other police of!cers who do. A journalist? You can promote an anti-racist form of reporting, cutting through the mysti- !cations of racial domination to clutch hold of the truth. A nurse? You can 278 M. Desmond and M. Emirbayer D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 strive to provide the same level of care to all patients, regardless of their racial identity or socioeconomic status – and you can pull strings for those who need help but lack health insurance, encouraging other nurses to do the same. A teacher? You can petition the school board to promote a multicul- tural curriculum; speak out against the racist practice of tracking; and teach your students about white privilege. A nutritionist? You can organize free classes in impoverished neighborhoods, giving lessons on how to live well and eat right. An artist? You can work with an anti-racist aesthetic and encourage fellow artists not to depict people of color in overly simplistic modes. A lawyer? You can !ght for civil rights and speak out against injus- tices within the criminal justice system. A business owner? You can make sure your !rm hires and promotes well-quali!ed people of color and that it is de!ned by a healthy and warm racial climate. We easily could go on, but the point is clear: We can be advocates for racial justice in any and all lines of work. If you work for change within your institutions, you will face obstacles and hardships. There might come a time when racial justice requires you to sacri!ce something important to you. It is one thing to write your boss an email, asking him why a white employee was promoted over a more quali- !ed non-white one. But what if you were the one promoted? Or perhaps you are a person of color who has climbed the ladder to a position of power within a company but whose very presence in that position allows the com- pany to get away with all kinds of discriminatory practices. Will you let your voice be heard, even if it threatens the position you worked so hard to attain? When you are looking for a home, will you move into a segregated gated community or invest in a multiracial neighborhood, perhaps in a less af"uent part of town with less attractive property values? Today and in the future, if you !ght for racial justice, you might be faced with some tough decisions. They are tough precisely because they require you to endure discomfort or hardship at the expense of doing the right thing. But, as Socrates said long ago, ‘it is better to suffer wrong than to do wrong’ (Arendt 2003, 151). What is needed is courage and integrity. Change never comes without sacri!ce. Those who fought in the Civil Rights Move- ment endured prison and beatings. They were humiliated and spat upon. They were !red from their jobs. Their children were threatened and shoved and punched and bullied to tears. They endured depression and weariness; insomnia and terror. Some endured their homes being !rebombed; some gave their lives to the movement. What will we endure? Can we expect whites to endure much, to set aside all claims to white privilege and actively to work against a system of racial domination from which they bene!t? Since the earliest days of the anti-racist movement in America, whites have spoken out against racial injustice and have been per- secuted, even killed, as a result (Thompson, Schaefer, and Bond 2003; Thompson 2001; Aptheker 1974 [1943]). In 1899, after emphasizing the Race Ethnicity and Education 279 D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 responsibility of non-whites in the liberation struggle, Du Bois wrote these words: ‘Discrimination is morally wrong, politically dangerous, industrially wasteful, and socially silly. It is the duty of whites to stop it, and to do so primarily for their own sakes’ (Du Bois 1996 [1899], 394). Why would Du Bois argue that whites should help put an end to racial domination, not sim- ply because it is the moral thing to do, but ‘for their own sakes’? The answer, of course, is that, despite the advantages whites enjoy on account of their skin privilege, whites, too, are af"icted by racial domina- tion. For one, by creating racial antagonisms within the working class, racial domination has reinforced non-white and white poverty. Moreover, racial domination is costly, and white taxpayers shoulder the bill when they pay for prisons, police of!cers, and super!cial !xes for old and entrenched social problems (Brown et al. 2003; Feagin et al. 2001). Racial domination, studies have shown, takes a psychological toll on whites, who live in fear of the racialized Other and with a good deal of guilt, depression, and shame (Spanierman et al. 2006). White people also suffer a kind of spiritual cost under the forces of racial domination. For their skin privileges, whites pay with a piece of their humanity. ‘The price of the liberation of the white peo- ple,’ Baldwin (1993 [1962], 97) would write, ‘is the liberation of the blacks [and, we add, all people of color] – the total liberation, in the cities, in the towns, before the law, and in the mind’. Collective action pitched at changing institutions complements individual- level action. Both approaches are important, but collective action is far more effective. If you want to effect real and lasting change within your institu- tions, then organize others to join you in pushing change forward. Start where you are, changing the institutions to which you currently belong: your social associations, religious organizations, political parties, and workplaces. How would we do this? We tender two simple guidelines: join and reach. As for joining, in most cases you do not have to start from scratch. You can seek out organizations already at work and lend a hand. Join a union or an anti- racist organization on campus or an interfaith alliance. And once you have joined, reach. Coalition-building means bringing others along with you in your pursuit of racial justice. Look for unlikely alliances; think of unusual connections. Seek out people in all areas of the institution to join your cause, from the mailroom to the corner of!ce. Above all, reach across racial divides. Turn your back on false divisions separating ‘Latino issues’ from ‘African American issues’ or ‘class issues’ from ‘race issues’ and instead pursue an agenda that unites these causes. Multiracial coalition building is bound to fail unless organizations widen their vision and critically assess how their pro- posed solutions to institutional problems produce differential effects across race (Fortier 2005). Consider an issue at the top of today’s feminist agenda: violence against women. If an organization working to protect women from abuse persuades the state to increase the severity of domestic violence laws, it may uninten- 280 M. Desmond and M. Emirbayer D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 tionally make things worse for victimized black women. The reason is that, because they are fully aware of the rampant inequalities faced by young black men within the criminal justice system, black women increasingly are reluctant to turn their abusers over to the police. In fact, studies have shown that, in black communities, the frequency of domestic violence calls decreases as the severity of domestic violence laws increases. The important point, one stressed over and over again by women of color, is that today’s feminist movement must be utterly multiracial if it hopes to address the problems of all women. Tokenism simply will not do. The voices of women of color must be heard throughout feminist organizations, and the feminist movement must address their problems with the same commitment and intelligence as it does those of white women (Roberts 1997; Collins 2000; Crenshaw 1991). Workers’ rights won by union mobilization demonstrate the importance of interracial alliances. Asian-American and Mexican-American farm work- ers, along with documented and undocumented immigrants, joined together to !ght for more rights and helped energize a movement that would eventu- ally result in the thoroughly multiracial United Farm Workers of America. Chicago’s white and black packinghouse workers, whom the business elite long had pitted against one another to drive down the price of labor, over- came ethnic and racial antagonisms to form the powerful United Packing- house Workers of America. In 1946, the interracial union went on strike to increase workers’ wages – and won. And Hawaii’s racially diverse working- class movement united native Hawaiian, Portuguese, Chinese, Japanese, and Filipino workers to win better pay and the institutionalization of antidiscrim- ination guidelines (Brueggemann and Boswell 1998; Halpern and Horowitz 1996; Barrett 1987; Jung 2003). In the tradition of the interracial labor movement, we can band together to bring about signi!cant change in our society. ‘Working in multiracial coalitions of equal members,’ writes Frank Wu, ‘united by shared principles, we can create communities that are diverse and just. Together, we can reinvent the civil rights movement’ (Wu 2002, 325). Nation Racial inequalities have persisted to this day in large part because, for far too long, the American state has refused to develop effective policies aimed at abolishing these disparities. The state has invested, and invested hand- somely, in mass incarceration, but it has invested meagerly in drug treatment or job creation programs. It has invested mightily in warfare and weapons technology but has invested meagerly in public education, head start pro- grams, or teachers’ salaries (Brown et al. 2003, 230). A national anti-racist movement would work to reverse these trends and to push for intelligent Race Ethnicity and Education 281 D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 ‘reforms that would ease the circumstances of people at the bottom of American society’ (Piven 2008, 1). How would we reform policy and social structure? How would we change our nation? Through ongoing, energetic, and collective political action. We can start by lobbying our elected of!cials, asking them to embrace anti-racist reforms. Write them letters; circulate and sign petitions; participate in Internet-based political movements; put our energies behind a candidate willing to !ght racism and volunteer for her or his campaign. And never fail to vote (Piven and Cloward 2000). These political activities are the bread-and-butter of democratic participation and the least we should do as politically engaged citizens. As history attests, however, bold reform and transformative social change are brought about, not only through such measures, but also – and primarily – through methods of public protest, including strikes, sustained boycotts, public demonstrations, civil disobedience, racial uprisings, and full-scale revolutions. Democracy entered the world through a revolution, and it is a revolution that we celebrate on the Fourth of July. Slavery was abolished because abolitionists employed revolutionary methods while agitating for slaves’ freedom – and because, as Du Bois pointed out, black slaves them- selves rose up in rebellion; women gained the right to vote because mem- bers of the suffrage movement took to the streets; union strikes during the beginning of the twentieth century helped boost thousands of workers from poverty into the middle class; the Vietnam War drew to a close because the powerful anti-war movement of the 1960s demanded it happen; and segrega- tion folded because anti-racist social movements forced its hand (Metzgar 2000; Piven 2008). In 1984, Cesar Chavez re"ected on a lifetime spent organizing farm workers with the words, ‘The UFW [United Farm Workers of America] was the beginning! We attacked that historical source of shame and infamy that our people in this country lived with. We attacked that injustice, not by complaining; not by seeking hand-outs; not by becoming soldiers in the War on Poverty. We organized! . . . [And in so doing,] we created con!dence and pride and hope in an entire people’s ability to create the future’ (Chavez 2008 [1979], 426). To participate in collective political action – to employ the time-honored methods of public protest – is to engage as fully and completely as possible in civil society and to refuse to ‘become victims in a democratic society.’ Of course, some social movements are more effective than others. Why do some movements succeed while others fail? Sociologists have devoted con- siderable effort to answering this question. In what follows, we organize their !ndings around seven components of successful political protest, stated here as injunctions. First, realize you have power. Society is fundamentally a collection of relations of mutual dependence. Workers rely on capitalists for a paycheck, but capitalists rely on workers’ labor; consumers rely on corporations for 282 M. Desmond and M. Emirbayer D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 their goods, but corporations depend on consumers’ buying their products; citizens are subject to politicians’ decisions, but they also hold great sway over politicians with the power of the vote; and we all depend on one another to uphold the laws and customs of civil society. When we acknowl- edge these relations of power – and determine how to exploit these relations – we have discovered the foundation of political protest. Second, build coalitions. The practice of coalition-building discussed under the rubric of institutional change applies as well to social movements !ghting for political or structural change. Successful movements accurately identify their targets, their adversaries, as well as their allies: many times, neither group is what one !rst expects. They also !nd ways of incorporating multiple institutions – religious organizations, social associations, student groups, unions – into their organizing efforts so that different institutions can work in concert with one another. To do so, they identify points of con- gruence with other social movements so as to widen their base and appeal (Meyer and Whittier 1994). Third, remember that the insurgency matters more than the insurgent organization. Protest organizations are extremely important and can get quite a lot accomplished, but formal organizations can sometimes end up discour- aging instead of promoting social unrest. As Frances Fox Piven and Richard Cloward point out in their important book, Poor People’s Movements, elites often are happy to comply, as they know it is insurgency, not insurgent organizations, they have to fear (Piven and Cloward 1977, xi–xii). The suc- cessful social movement, then, has its priorities in line. It realizes that the power is in the mob not the meeting – that what is powerful is organizing not the organization – and it does not squander rare opportunities to breathe fresh life into the discontented masses. Fourth, exploit weaknesses in the dominant system. Racial domination is old and powerful, it is true; but it is not a total system, immune to chal- lenges. The smartest social movements !nger its structures, !nd the weak spots, and tear them open. They identify simple strategies that can have large and far-reaching effects. Even individual acts of agitation can throw off the system of racial domination. Each of us, in our own fashion, can ‘throw [our] grain of sand into the well-oiled machinery of resigned com- plicities’ (Bourdieu 2003, 65). Fifth, do not be afraid to break some rules. Some laws are just; others are not. Successful social movements do not allow unjust laws to stand in their way. This is the central idea undergirding civil disobedience, that tactic of protest upon which the Civil Rights Movement relied so heavily – and with great success. Throughout the history of America, people have found it impossible to act justly while obeying an unjust law. For a new society to burst forth, the unjust rules holding it back had to be snapped. In his essay, Resistance to Civil Government, Henry David Thoreau put it this way: ‘If it is of such a nature that it requires you to be the agent of injustice to another, Race Ethnicity and Education 283 D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 then I say, break the law. Let your life be a counter-friction to stop the machine.’ Sixth, plan for the long haul. The successful social movement develops strategies to support its members throughout the organizing campaign, espe- cially if those people are participating in political action that causes them some hardship. In many cases, activists need to !gure out, not only how to mobilize together, but also how to live together, how to survive the insur- gency without acquiescing to systems of domination. This is especially important in this day and age, when one !nds many avowed anti-racist peo- ple but very few organized anti-racist activists – and where resistance to fundamental racial change remains strong (Hero and Preuhs 2006; Winant 2004, 57–62). Finally, have fun. A peculiar injunction? Perhaps, but organizing against racial domination is dif!cult work. People often disagree about the funda- mental nature of the problem and how, precisely, to confront it. One person might suggest that her organization focus on children’s education; another might point to the family unit; and still another might suggest concentrating efforts on housing, prison, job-creation, community revitalization, or any number of things. The scarcity of any organization’s time and resources requires the narrowing of objectives; and choosing to confront one problem over another often leads to serious inter-organizational con"ict. Agendas clash, especially within coalitions comprising a diverse array of activists. Matters pertaining to the gay community or women of color might be raised; some members of the coalition might charge the organization with paying too much attention to ‘Mexican issues’ (like immigration) or ‘black issues’ (like inner-city poverty) and not enough attention to ‘American Indian issues’ (like environmental racism) or problems confronting poor whites (like rural poverty). The magnitude and depth of the problem as well as inter-organizational con"ict might lead those who hope to struggle against racial domination to grow weary and burn out. Or they might fall in love with their outrage, overlooking the perhaps small but nonetheless signi!cant victories (Gitlin 2003, 143). Activists might grow bitter and pessimistic and perhaps not recognize the triumph of justice even if it comes. This is why it becomes so important to laugh together. Those in a healthy social movement share stories and jokes; they horse around and pull pranks; they respect one another and look forward to working together. They are forward-thinking and optimistic, holding fast to the truism that we have come a long way and can go much farther. They believe in the promise of democracy. In such a social movement, power is evenly distributed throughout the organization, and control is not monopolized by a cadre of ‘elite activists’ (and neither is the brunt of the labor). Working toward racial justice may require sacri!ce; it undoubtedly will result in frustration, anger, and feelings of defeat. But, ask any activist, it will also give you a deep sense of purpose and joy. When you work for something bigger than yourself, something more important 284 M. Desmond and M. Emirbayer D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 than your checking account or your personal ambitions, life grows "ush with meaning and importance. The next word ‘It does not require a majority to prevail but rather an irate, tireless minority keen to set brush!res in people’s minds.’ Samuel Adams, one of America’s founding fathers, offered these famous lines, words that ring true up to this very hour. It is necessary to remind ourselves time and again that during the Civil Rights Movement, the majority of white and non-white Americans stood on the sidelines while a core cadre of committed activists pushed the country forward. The same is true of most major historical events. Analysts have referred to it as the 80/20 phenomenon: the common observation that roughly 80% of social change is brought about by 20% of the population. Sociologist Mario Small (2004, 177) has gone even further, suggesting that a community association that involves less than 1% of the total neighbor- hood population can bring about signi!cant social change in that neighbor- hood. When a few impassioned citizens gather together around a single cause, the potential to move the world is in their hands. ‘Idealist and naïve,’ dis- misses the cynic, coldly and con!dently pointing to the countless times peo- ple have tried and failed. Yes, there have been failures aplenty – power never cedes ground easily – but we owe many of the freedoms we enjoy today to idealistic souls who joined hands and marched forward as the cyn- ics snickered off to the side. Collective action is most effective when people break down the racial cleavages that slice civil society into a hundred different groups. The Civil Rights Movement is a prime example of this, for the movement was never more powerful than when blacks were able to incorporate other non-whites and whites into their liberation struggle (Alexander 2006). ‘The present problem of problems,’ Du Bois (1999 [1920], 33) once remarked, ‘is noth- ing more than democracy beating itself helplessly against the color bar, – purling, seeping, seething, foaming to burst through. . . [but] held back by those who dream of future kingdoms of greed built on black and brown and yellow slavery.’ Democracy has poked through the veil bit by bit, letting some light through with each advance, but its full potential has yet to be unleashed upon America. This article has provided some guidance for how we might advance the march of a multicultural democracy, ways we can address racial domination. We have speci!ed three ends – intended to provide a picture of possibilities that, once in our line of vision, may be used to direct and galvanize engaged citizens – as well as some guidelines for how we might go about achieving these ends. So much more could be said – and we invite you to say it. The next word is yours. Race Ethnicity and Education 285 D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 References Abu-Lughod, L. 1991. Writing against culture. In Recapturing anthropology: Work- ing in the present, ed. R. Fox. Santa Fe, NM: School of American Research Press. Alexander, J. 2006. The civil sphere. New York: Oxford University Press. Appiah, K.A. 2006. Cosmopolitanism: Ethics in a world of strangers. New York: Norton. Apple, M. 1999. The absent presence of race in educational reform. Race Ethnicity and Education 2: 9–16. Aptheker, H. 1974 [1943]. American Negro slave revolts. New York: International. Arendt, H. 1978. The life of the mind, volume two: Willing. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich. Arendt, H. 2003. Responsibility and judgment. New York: Schocken Books. Baldwin, J. 1993 [1962]. The "re next time. New York: Vintage. Banks, J. 2002. Race, knowledge construction, and education in the USA: Lessons from history. Race Ethnicity and Education 5: 7–27. Banting, K., and W. Kymlicka. 2006. Introduction: Multiculturalism and the welfare state: Setting the context. In Multiculturalism and the welfare state: Recognition and redistribution in contemporary democracies, ed. K. Banting and W. Kymli- cka, 1–48. New York: Oxford University Press. Barrett, J. 1987. Work and community in the jungle: Chicago’s packinghouse work- ers, 1894–1922. Bloomington: University of Illinois Press. Barry, B. 2001. Culture and equality: An egalitarian critique of multiculturalism. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Bell, D. 1987. And we are not saved: The elusive quest for racial justice. New York: Basic Books. Bonilla-Silva, E. 2003. Racism without racists: Color-blind racism and the persis- tence of racial inequality in the United States. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Lit- tle!eld. Borjas, G. 1990. Friends or strangers: The impact of immigrants on the U.S. econ- omy. New York: Basic Books. Borjas, G., and M. Tienda. 1987. The economic consequences of immigration. Sci- ence 235: 645–52. Bourdieu, P. 2003. Firing back: Against the tyranny of the market 2, 17–25. New York: New Press. Brown, M., M. Carnoy, E. Currie, T. Duster, D. Oppenheimer, M. Shultz, and D. Wellman. 2003. White-washing race: The myth of a color blind society. Berke- ley: University of California Press. Brubaker, R., and F. Cooper. 2000. Beyond identity. Theory and Society 29: 1–47. Brueggemann, J., and T. Boswell. 1998. Realizing solidarity: Sources of interracial unionism during the Great Depression. Work and Occupations 25: 436–82. Chavez, C. 2008 [1979]. Address to the Commonwealth Club of California, 1984. Freedom in America, ed. Kenneth Bridges, 424-30. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson, Prentice Hall. Cohen, J., and J. Rogers. 1993. Associations and democracy. Social Philosophy and Policy 10: 282–312. Collins, P.H. 2000. Black feminist thought: Knowledge, consciousness, and the poli- tics of empowerment, 2nd ed. New York: Routledge. Cooley, C.H. 1966 [1918]. Social process. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press. 286 M. Desmond and M. Emirbayer D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 Crenshaw, K. 1991. Mapping the margins: Intersectionality, identity politics, and violence against women of color. Stanford Law Review 43: 1241–99. Cronon, W. 1998. ‘Only connect. . .’: The goals of a liberal education. The Ameri- can Scholar 67: 73–80. Dewey, J. 1988 [1920]. Reconstruction in philosophy. In John Dewey: The middle works, 1899-1924, Vol. 12: 1920. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.. Dewey, J. 1988 [1929]. The quest for certainty, The later works, 1925-1953, Vol. 4: 1929. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press. Du Bois, W.E.B. 1996 [1899]. The Philadelphia Negro: A social study. Philadel- phia: University of Pennsylvania Press. Du Bois, W.E.B. 1999 [1920]. Darkwater: Voices from within the veil. New York: Dover. Fanon, F. 2004 [1963]. The wretched of the earth. New York: Grove. Feagin, J., and H. Vera. 2001. Liberation sociology. Cambridge: Westview. Feagin, J.R., H. Vera, and P. Batur. 2001. White racism: The basics, 2nd ed. New York: Routledge. Figueroa, P. 1999. Multiculturalism and anti-racism in a new era: A critical review. Race Ethnicity and Education 2: 281–302. Ford, R.T. 2005. Racial culture: A critique. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Fortier, A.-M. 2005. Pride politics and multiculturalist citizenship. Ethnic and Racial Studies 28: 559–78. Fuchs, L. 1992. Thinking about immigration and ethnicity in the United States. In Immigration in two democracies: French and American experience, ed. D. Horowitz and G. Noiriel, 39–65. New York: New York University Press. Gitlin, T. 1996. The twilight of common dreams: Why America is wracked by cul- ture wars. New York: Henry Holt and Company. Gitlin, T. 2003. Letters to a young activist. New York: Basic Books. Gotanda, N. 2000. A critique of ‘Our Constitution is Color-Blind’. In Critical race theory: The cutting edge. 2nd ed., ed. R. Delgato and J. Stefancic, 35–8. Phila- delphia: Temple University Press. Habermas, J. 2003. Intolerance and discrimination. International Journal of Consti- tutional Law 1: 2–12. Hacker, J., and P. Pierson. 2005. Off center: The republican revolution and the ero- sion of American democracy. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Halpern, R., and R. Horowitz. 1996. Meatpackers: An oral history of black pack- inghouse workers and their struggle for racial and economic equality. New York: Twayne Publishers. Harvey, D. 2005. A brief history of neoliberalism. New York: Oxford University Press. Hero, R., and R. Preuhs. 2006. Multiculturalism and welfare politics in the USA: A state-level comparative analysis. In Multiculturalism and the welfare state: Recognition and redistribution in contemporary democracies, ed. K. Banting and W. Kymlicka, 121–51. New York: Oxford University Press. Huxley, A. 1998 [1932]. Brave new world. New York: Perennial. Jackson, D. 1996. Facts favor af!rmative action. The Boston Globe, October 30: A17. Jung, M.-K. 2003. Interracialism: The ideological transformation of Hawaii’s work- ing class. American Sociological Review 68: 373–400. Race Ethnicity and Education 287 D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 Katz, J. 1978. White awareness: A handbook for anti-racism training. Norman: Oklahoma University Press. Katznelson, I. 2005. When af"rmative action was white: The untold history of racial inequality in twentieth-century America. New York: Norton. Kivel, P. 2002 [1997]. Uprooting racism: How white people can work for racial justice, revised ed. Gabriola Island, BC: New Society Publishers. Kymlicka, W. 1995. Multicultural citizenship: A liberal theory of minority rights. New York: Oxford University Press. Lewin, K. 1951. Field theory in social science: Selected theoretical papers. New York: Harper and Row. Metzgar, J. 2000. Striking steel: Solidarity remembered. Philadelphia: Temple Uni- versity Press. Meyer, D., and N. Whittier. 1994. Social movement spillover. Social Problems 4: 277–98. Mills, C.W. 1959. The sociological imagination. New York: Oxford University Press. Morin, R. 1997. Unconventional wisdom. The Washington Post, January 12: CO5. Mullings, L. 2005. Interrogating racism: Toward an antiracist anthropology. Annual Review of Anthropology 24: 667–93. Nemiroff, R. 1969. To be young gifted and black: A portrait of Lorraine Hansberry in her own words. New York: Samuel French. Norton, E.H. 1996. Af!rmative action in the workplace. In The af"rmative action debate, ed. G. Curry, 39–48. Reading: Addison-Wesley. Patterson, O. 1998. The ordeal of integration: Progress and resentment in America’s ‘racial’ crisis. New York: Basic Civitas Books. Pedersen, A., I. Walker, and M. Wise. 2005. ‘Talk does not cook rice’: Beyond anti-racism rhetoric to strategies for social action. Australian Psychologist 40: 20–30. Phillips, A. 2007. Multiculturalism without culture. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univer- sity Press. Piven, F.F. 2008. Can power from below change the world? American Sociological Review 73: 1–14. Piven, F.F., and R. Cloward. 1977. Poor people’s movements: Why they succeed, how they fail. New York: Pantheon. Piven, F.F., and R. Cloward. 2000. Why Americans still don’t vote: And why politi- cians want it that way. Boston: Beacon Press. Polanyi, K. 2001 [1944]. The great transformation: The political and economic ori- gins of our time. Boston: Beacon. Reskin, B. 1998. The realities of af"rmative action. Washington, DC: American Sociological Association. Rich, M., and A. Castelan Cargile. 2004. Beyond the breach: Transforming white identities in the classroom. Race Ethnicity and Education 7: 351–65. Roberts, D. 1997. Killing the black body: Race, reproduction, and the meaning of liberty. New York: Pantheon. Sartre, J.-P. 2004 [1963]. Preface. In The wretched of the earth, F. Fanon. New York: Grove. Small, M. 2004. Villa Victoria: The transformation of social capital in a Boston barrio. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Smith, R. 1999. Toward a more perfect union: Beyond old liberalism and neoliber- alism. In Without justice for all: The new liberalism and our retreat from racial equality, ed. A. Reed, Jr., 327–53. Boulder, CO: Westview Press. 288 M. Desmond and M. Emirbayer D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 Spanierman, L., V. Paul Poteat, A. Beer, and P.I. Armstrong. 2006. Psychological costs of racism to whites: Exploring patterns through cluster analysis. Journal of Counseling Psychology 53: 434–41. Stephen, W., and K. Finlay. 1999. The role of empathy in improving intergroup relations. Journal of Social Issues 55: 729–43. Tatum, B.D. 1997. ‘Why are all the black kids sitting together in the cafeteria’ and other conversations about race. New York: Basic Books. Taylor, C. 1994. The politics of recognition. In Multiculturalism: Examining the politics of recognition, ed. A. Gutmann, 25–74. Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univer- sity Press. Thompson, B. 2001. A promise and a way of life: White antiracist activism. Minne- apolis: University of Minnesota Press. Thompson, C., E. Schaefer, and H. Bond. 2003. White men challenging racism: 35 personal stories. Durham, NC: Duke University Press. Wacquant, L. 2007. Urban outcasts: A comparative sociology of advanced margin- ality. Cambridge: Polity Press. Western, B. 2006. Punishment and inequality in America. New York: Russell Sage Foundation. Wiesel, E. 1986. Quoted in US News & World Report, October 27, 1986. Willett, C. 2001. The soul of justice: Social bonds and racial hubris. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Winant, H. 2001. The world is a ghetto: Race and democracy since World War II. New York: Basic Books. Winant, H. 2004. The new politics of race: Globalism, difference, justice. Minneap- olis: University of Minnesota Press. Wright, E.O. 2003. Preface: The real utopias project. In Deepening democracy: Institutional innovations in empowered participatory governance, ed. A. Fung, and E.O. Wright, vii–viii. London: Verso. Wright, E.O. 2010. Envisioning real utopias. London: Verso. Wu, F. 2002. Yellow: Race in America beyond black and white. New York: Basic Books. Race Ethnicity and Education 289 D ow nl oa de d by [H ar va rd C ol le ge ] a t 0 6: 54 2 9 N ov em be r 2 01 2 work_h7ivac2ynzaofaykd7ek6qvkoi ---- Northumbria Research Link Citation: Wilson, Tim (2016) Criminal justice and global public goods: The Prüm Forensic Biometric Cooperation. The Journal of Criminal Law, 80 (5). pp. 303-326. ISSN 0022-0183 Published by: SAGE URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0022018316668450 This version was downloaded from Northumbria Research Link: http://nrl.northumbria.ac.uk/27800/ Northumbria University has developed Northumbria Research Link (NRL) to enable users to access the University’s research output. Copyright © and moral rights for items on NRL are retained by the individual author(s) and/or other copyright owners. Single copies of full items can be reproduced, displayed or performed, and given to third parties in any format or medium for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-profit purposes without prior permission or charge, provided the authors, title and full bibliographic details are given, as well as a hyperlink and/or URL to the original metadata page. The content must not be changed in any way. Full items must not be sold commercially in any format or medium without formal permission of the copyright holder. The full policy is available online: http://nrl.northumbria.ac.uk/pol i cies.html This document may differ from the final, published version of the research and has been made available online in accordance with publisher policies. To read and/or cite from the published version of the research, please visit the publisher’s website (a subscription may be required.) http://nrl.northumbria.ac.uk/policies.html Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 1 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 CRIMINAL JUSTICE AND GLOBAL PUBLIC GOODS: THE PRÜM FORENSIC BIOMETRIC COOPERATION MODEL Tim J Wilson Professor of Criminal Justice Policy, School of Law, Northumbria University, Newcastle UK [As unnumbered footnote Corresponding author: Tim J Wilson, School of Law, Northumbria University, Northumbria University, Newcastle City Campus, 2 Ellison Pl, Newcastle upon Tyne NE1 8ST, UK. E-mail: tim.wilson@northumbria.ac.uk.] Abstract This article places sharing forensic biometric data for international criminal justice cooperation purposes within the domain of global public goods. Such cooperation is a rational response to globalization, but faces several obstacles. These range from socio-cultural and political concerns about national legal and criminal justice autonomy to the potential impact of market fundamentalism on scientific standardization and cooperation mechanism delivery. The significance of such inhibitors will vary as societal and personal perceptions of stability change. These issues are examined by analysing the progress achieved with the EU Prüm forensic biometric data exchange model. Shocks to European stability, such as the increased scale of terrorist crimes and the UK EU referendum result will inevitably test the resilience of Prüm. Combining insights from global public goods and criminal law scholarship, however, may help to identify how reactions to such shocks, including questions about future UK participation in Prüm, might be managed. Keywords International criminal justice cooperation; global public goods; forensic science standardization; market fundamentalism/neoliberalism; Brexit Introduction This article responds to the publication of Forensic Science and Beyond: Authenticity, Provenance and Assurance (hereinafter Walport) by addressing the three policy objectives falling within the Chief Scientific Adviser’s remit, namely: (a) identifying how significant emerging technology might be exploited either directly or indirectly in the national interest, (b) providing evidence to support policy making and (c) improving national resilience and security. 1 1 M. Walport, Annual Report of the Government Chief Scientific Adviser 2015: Forensic Science and Beyond: Authenticity, Provenance and Assurance vol. 1 (Government Office for Science: London 2015) 4. Available at https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/506461/gs-15-37a-forensic- science-beyond-report.pdf (accessed 14 July 2016). mailto:tim.wilson@northumbria.ac.uk https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/506461/gs-15-37a-forensic-science-beyond-report.pdf https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/506461/gs-15-37a-forensic-science-beyond-report.pdf Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 2 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 Following an earlier chapter commissioned for Walport, it invests them with an international dimension, but differs from its precursor in three respects. 2 Firstly, it focuses exclusively on one scientific or technological development: the automated exchange of forensic bioinformation (DNA and finger/palmprints) data. Secondly, following the UK Refendum, consideration will be given to how this might affect UK policy making that had only several months before settled on and had obtained political approval to join Prüm. Thirdly, it considers the future prospects for the Prüm model following major shocks within the EU from terrorist crimes, which could result in a greater emphasis on security (hereinafter ‘securitization’) in international criminal justice cooperation. 3 Neither Prüm nor the international criminal justice cooperation this facilitates is a ‘final global public good’. Instead this data sharing is treated as an ‘intermediate input’ into the production of a global public good or goods. 4 Comparisons from public health are, respectively, the development of pharmaceutical knowledge and the eradication of polio. 5 Loader and Walker similarly refer to transnational policing as an intermediate input to the final good of security. 6 Therefore this article seeks to answer the following questions (a) is Prüm an effective model as an intermediate input into a global public good(s) and (b), if so, (i) why, (ii) how stable is this approach and (iii), given the Walport focus of this special issue, what are the implications of the EU Referendum results for UK law and policy making towards this model of international criminal justice cooperation? Irespective of how the final and intermediate input to the public good (or goods) are described, arguably criminal justice cooperation brings to international development the doctrinal robustness of law. This may complement the normatively rich attributes of public goods, such as government free from the taint of corruption or more generically goods contributing to the improvement of human life. This assumption is tested by the mullti-disciplinary approach in this article that enables significant congruency to be highlighted between global public goods research findings and various legal doctrines. Global public goods is a concept that originated in development economics. It was primarily intended to improve international decision making –in response to globalisation - for the benefit of poorer countries. There is a clear argument for locating Prüm in this domain. International criminal justice cooperation supports UN Sustainable Development Goal 16.3: ‘promote the rule of law at 2 T. Wilson, ‘The Global Perspective’ in M. Peplow (ed.), Annual Report of the Government Chief Scientific Adviser 2015: Forensic Science and Beyond: Authenticity, Provenance and Assurance: Evidence and Case Studies 82-93Available at https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/506462/gs-15-37b-forensic- science-beyond-evidence.pdf ( accessed 14 July 2016). 3 The term ‘securitization’ is used in this article to denote an increased emphasis within criminal justice agencies, such as police services, and their international cooperation activities on protection and prevention against security risks (including terrorism) and not in its more usual financial sense of how assets are used to guarantee loans. 4 P. Eigen and C. Eigen-Zucchi, ‘Corruption and Global Public Goods’ in I. Kaul, P. Conceição, K. Le Goulven and R.U. Mendoza (eds.), Providing Global Public Goods: Managing Globalisation (OUP, New York: 2003) at 583. 5 I. Kaul and R.U. Mendoza, ‘Advancing the Concept of Public Goods’ in Kaul et al., above n.4 at 80-89 and P Eigen and C Eigen-Zucchi, above n.4 at 576-597. 6 I. Loader and N. Walker, ‘Locating the Public Interest in Transnational Policing’ in A. Goldsmith and J. Sheptycki (eds.), Crafting Transnational Policing: Police Capacity-Building and Global Policing Reform (Hart, Oxford: 2007), n.2 117-118. https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/506462/gs-15-37b-forensic-science-beyond-evidence.pdf https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/506462/gs-15-37b-forensic-science-beyond-evidence.pdf Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 3 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 national and international levels and ensure equal access to justice for all’ 7 . Deference to such ideals is found in many criminal justice cooperation texts, but may be combined with more normatively ambiguous objectives. For example, the EU- US Mutual Legal Assistance (MLA) agreement refers to the ’consolidation of the rule of law and respect for human rights and humanitarian law, as well as the preservation of peace’ and then adds ‘and the strengthening of international security’. 8 Kaul and Mendoza have observed how ‘as national borders become porous and cross-border economic activity increases, these goods become indivisible across borders or transnational’. 9 Globalisation has created an impetus for the promotion of criminal justice cooperation. It has also, particularly with terorist crimes, ceased to be geographically remote throughout the EU and has gained ‘a civil dimension’, thus blurring possible distinctions between criminal justice and security cooperation. 10 National boundaries (even maritime borders) are increasingly irrelevant economically and socially, offering little check to unauthorised entry or protection against transnational offending. 11 Similarly in a liberal democracy, at a theoretical level, criminal justice conforms to the two defining characteristics of publicness: (a) non-excludability (the producer cannot exclude any person from benefitting from it) and (b) non-rivalry (consumption by one person does not diminish its availabilty for others). 12 It is possible to classify global public goods on the basis of ‘the nature of their publicness and the conditions of their provision’ (for example natural or human-made). 13 What appears to be more pertinent, however, in a criminal justice context is how to structure cooperation to achieve ‘globalness managed to mutual advantage’. This is seen within a global public goods context, as placing the onus of proof on those proposing an international solution to justify such a strategy. 14 This offers an intial example of a degree of congruence between global public goods and legal doctrine. The former might justify an approach to international negotiations. Should the negotiations eventually result in rights-limiting legislation (inevitable with forensic bioinformation), the necessity stage of proportionality analysis places a similar requirement on the state during judicial review. The article begins by describing the principal theoretical and empirical issues covered.These arise from four factors: (i) the social nature of the good and, in the case of forensic bioinformation, an interrelationship with privacy and data protection; (ii) difficulties for policy making and resource allocation stemming from poor data about the impact of criminal justice initiatives and the burden of 7 United Nations, General Assembly, Report of the Open Working Group of the General Assembly on Sustainable Development Goals, A/68/970, August 2014 . Available at https://sustainabledevelopment.un.org/focussdgs.html (accessed 13 April 2016). 8 Agreement on Mutual Legal Assistance between the European Union and the United States, 25 June 2003, OJ L 181/34. 9 See Kaul and Mendoza, above n.5 at 97. 10 S. Medvedev and I.Tomashov, ‘Security as a Global Public Good: Common Issues for the European Union and the G8’ in M.V. Larionova (ed.), The European Union in the G8: Promoting Consensus and Concerted Actions for Global Public Goods (Ashgate, Farnham, 2012) 214. 11 Home Affairs Committee, Migration Crisis (HC 2016–17, 24) paras 27-33. 12 This article is concerned with access to justice at a theoretical level. The delivery of justice as a public good requires adequate Legal Aid funding, etc. 13 S. Medvedev and I. Tomashov, ‘The Concept and Definition of Global Public Goods’ in M. Lavrionova, above n.10 at 17-20. 14 I. Kaul, P. Conceição, K. Le Goulven and R.U. Mendoza, ‘Why do Global Public Goods Matter today?’ in in I. Kaul et al., above n. 4 at 12. https://sustainabledevelopment.un.org/focussdgs.html Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 4 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 proof in relation to proportionality; (iii) the extent to which the Prüm model might reflect an asymmetrical distribution of power within the EU resulting in pressure on weaker members to internalise the costs of crime; and (iv) public law concerns about the scope of EU criminal law and socio-cultural notions of national sovereignty. This section ends with a brief description of the key features of Prüm to explain how this model for criminal justice cooperation sidesteps all or some of politico-legal issues. The second section consists of an empirically based analysis of how the criminological externalities of cross-border travel within Europe assume an increasingly global character. This also illustrates how the Prüm system can generate decision-informing data about trends in these externalities or ‘public bads’ of globalization. Both may have probative relevance to proportionality in respect of rights-limiting law relating to the use of forensic bioinformation. The third and fourth sections consider the lessons from the Prüm model and alternative options for cooperation. The first key delivery issue is the extent to which Prüm implementation both ultimately depended on and possibly incentivised international scientific standardization. The second consideration is the significant national legal and institutional effort required for implementation. Both issues raise questions about the assumptions underlying market fundamentalism. The final section begins by considering the future stability of this model, particularly in the light of convergence between EC and US security policy that is accelerating because of terrorist crimes. It addresses whether an awareness of potential congruence between global public goods theory and various legal doctrines might heighten awareness of the strengths of the Prüm model in the face of the potential securitization of EU criminal justice cooperation. These issues are then brought together in the conclusion by considering their implications of this for potential UK post-Referendum options for sharing forensic biometric data for international criminal justice cooperation purposes. The Delivery and Analysis of Global Public Goods with a Criminal Justice Dimension Since the late 1990s there has been a greater appreciation of the ‘negative spillovers from the the inadequate supply of transnational public goods, notably those stemming from communicable diseases, environmental degradation, spreading conflicts and financial instability’. 15 This has introduced significant legal issues into international development debates, but global public goods with criminal justice aspects feature less prominently in policy making and research. 16 Loader and Walker – when locating international policing in the domain of global public goods - identified two elements that distinguish security from purely economic public goods, such as environmental degradation. First, an added dimension: the root problem is socially generated. Second – unlike the more objective (or at least more quantifiable) provision of a classic economic good (e.g. housing) - perceptions of security/insecurity greatly depend on each person’s subjective assessment of the 15 T. Sandler, Assessing the Optimal Provision of Public Goods: In Search of the Holy Grail’ in Kaul et al., above n.4 at 131. 16 For example, the legal focus in the 2000 Millennium Development Goals (MDGs) was international trade, finance and governance related. Available at http://www.unmillenniumprojEct.org/goals/gti.htm#goal8 (accessed 14 July 2016). Criminal justice and even security is overshadowed by such issues in the main publications by Kaul and her colleagues. http://www.unmillenniumproject.org/goals/gti.htm#goal8 Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 5 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 social order. 17 The second observation should be qualified by noting how significant increases in recorded crime coincided with fairly widespread social uncertainties during the early stages of intensified globalisation. 18 A similar significance might be attached to the rising general anxiety about terrorism. Legal analysis dating back to the inception of Prüm, however, helps to place this second element (a personal peception of threats and their potential consequencies) onto a more extended and justiciable continuum. International criminal justice cooperation involving the exchange of sensitive personal information, such DNA and fingerprint data, will result ( in terms of Article 8 ECHR), in an inteference with privacy and requires effective data protection in all the countries involved. 19 There is a further complication. This arises from the comparatively poor quality of criminal justice data. UK criminal justice policy rarely demonstrates rigorous evidence-based decision-making. Politicians acknowledge in their more candid moments to being ‘driven more by considerations of political advantage than by appeals to evidence’. 20 Nevertheless, if it is hypothesised that decision making in international development and global cooperation more generally is expert dominated (e.g. climate change initiatives), the insufficient range, depth and quality of data relating to criminal justice could be a significant handicap when resources for the delivery of global public goods are rationed. Prüm, however, can assist decision making in such circumstances. It can be used to produce analyses of certain kinds of transnational offences or offending. 21 Such analyses may address also the burden of proof should the proportionality of the law relating to criminal justice cooperation be challenged. 22 It has been argued that the adoption of Prüm evidences an asymmetrical distribution of power or influence in policy making within the EU. This again is chiefly dealt with later, but what follows about the general EU legal context and the specific structure of Prum is relevant to this issue. As Marper makes clear, ECtHR, through the margin of appreciation, gives Convention signatory states very wide discretion over the collection, retention and use of forensic biometric data. 23 Within the EU legal order, the paramount authority of the member states over criminal justice and security is recognised in the treaties. 24 This, however, exists to some extent in a state of tension with developing CJEU case law from Pupino onwards. 25 It is worth noting from a Brexit perspective, that Prime Minster May (as Home Secretary) accepted that bi-lateral criminal justice cooperation with 17 See Loader and Walker, above n. 6 at 114-115. 18 N. Lacey, The Prisoners’ Dilemma: Political Economy and Punishment in Contemporary Democracies (CUP, Cambridge: 2008) 20-29. 19 The leading case is S & Marper v. The United Kingdom App no 30562/04 (ECtHR, 4 December 2008). See also for references to separate data protection issues, E.J. Kindt, Privacy and Data Protection Issues of Biometric Applications (Springer: Dordrecht, 2013) 221. 20 D. Faulkner and R. Burnett, Where Next for Criminal Justice? (The Policy Press, Bristol: 2012) 53. 21 For the definition of these terms see Wilson, above n.2 at 82. 22 For a recent critical analysis of the proportionality test see: J. Rivers, ‘The Presumption of Proportionality’ (2014) 77(3) MLR 409-433. 23 See Marper, above n. 19 [125]. 24 Article 4(2) TEU: ‘The Union shall respect the … State functions [of Member States], including …, maintaining law and order and safeguarding national security. 25 Case C-105/03 Pulpino [2005] ECR I-5285. Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 6 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 the EU, even for a country still well embedded within the TEU and TFEU as Denmark, is subject to CJEU jurisdiction. 26 ) This is potentially problematic from a human rights perspective because of the uncertain and perhaps unpromising jurisdictional interface between ECtHR and the CJEU. 27 Also Herlin-Karnell’s constitutionally focused analysis of EU criminal law suggests that its competence is far too imprecise and its development has been ad hoc rather than strategic, reflecting perhaps an inadequate knowledge of criminal law within its institutions, including the CJEU. 28 These legal and bio-ethical concerns intersect with Loader and Walker’s analysis of the obstacles to international policing as an intermediate public good. This stems from recognising tensions in the social and cultural dimensions of publicness, particularly a significant ‘socio-historical limitation’: … the sense of mutual trust, common engagement and general readiness to put things in common has been and remains strongly associated with the national state… … despite the deepening of global interdependence, the growth of institutions of global governance, and an arguably greater public conciousness of both these developments, sentiments of trust, loyalty and abstract solidarity remain stuck at national or subnational levels ... 29 This gives rise to the notion within the public goods literature on security to cooperation asymmetry (‘… governments remain extremely reluctant to cooperate on security matters …, terrorists have cooperated in networks since the onset of modern day terorism …’). 30 These convergent concerns help to shape views about the potential limits and modalities of EU criminal justice and/or security cooperation policies. These socio-cultural considerations are also congruent to debate about the scope of EU criminal law, which following extensive analysis Herlin- Karnell argues should be restricted to (a) ‘financial crimes ... linked to the concept of market creation’ and (b) the response to cross-border offending. 31 Prüm, in addition to satisfying the most abstemious prescription for the competence of EU criminal law – as a model of criminal justice cooperation – neatly sidesteps these socio-cultural problems. 32 This is so fundamental a point that it is necessary now to briefly describe the key features of the Prüm model. 26 HC Deb, 10 July 2014 vol 584, col 487. 27 S. Douglas-Scott, ‘The Relationship Between the EU and The ECHR Five Years on from the Treaty Of Lisbon’, University of Oxford Legal Research Paper Series, Paper No XX/2015. 28 E. Herlin-Karnell, The Constitutional Dimension of European Criminal Law (Hart, Oxford: 2012). 29 Above n.6 115-116. 30 T. Sandler, ‘Recognizing The Limits To Cooperation Behind National Borders: Financing The Control Of Transnational Terrorism’ in I. Kaul and P. Conceiçào (eds), The New public Finance: Responding To Global Challenges (OUP, New York: 2006) 195. 31 See Herlin-Karnell above n. 28 at 237. 32 The main legal instrument is Council Decision 2008/615/JHA of 23 June 2008 on the stepping up of cross- border cooperation, particularly in combating terrorism and cross-border crime. For a more detailed description of the Prüm arrangements see: H. Soleto Muñoz and A. Fiodorova, ‘DNA and Law Enforcement in the European Union: Tools and Human Rights Protection’, (2014) Utrecht Law Review 10 149-162. Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 7 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 Already a legal obligation for all but one of the current EU member states, the Westminster Parliament (cognizant of support from the Scottish government and the Northern Irish administration) voted in December 2015 to reverse a previous UK opt-out. 33 Iceland and Norway are members of Prüm, but not yet operational, and Switzerland has applied to join. 34 The system operates as a two stage process, but for brevity only the DNA arrangements are described here. During stage 1 anonymous data (DNA profiles are a series of numbers inputted into a digital form in standardized genetic format) are sent, usually daily, to each member state to which the transmitting country is connected for Prüm data exchange purposes. The anonymous data will only be retained in the receiving country if (a) there is an automatic ‘hit’ and (b) that ‘hit’ is scientifically valid (i.e. as a scientifically valid ‘match’) and (c) the case is of sufficient gravity, for personal details to be shared during Prüm Stage 2 about the known individual to whom the DNA profile relates. 35 However, a match between DNA profiles that are anonymous in both countries (i.e. because both were based on the DNA (a ‘trace’) of an unknown person) may, subject to national laws and inter-state agreements, be used to analyse trends etc. in cross-border offending. The key doctrinal issue arising in respect of the international exchange of forensic biometric data is proportionality. Specifically, following Marper, whether the use to which such data is put is proportionate and strikes a fair balance between the competing public and private interests. 36 The Prüm legislation, however, ensures that any questions in relation to this will be determined by relevant national laws – where in Marper ECtHR acknowledged the existence of a very wide margin of of appreciation - and not the EU framework itself. Thus, Prüm provides major scope for the national legal autonomy recognised by the the margin of apprectiation to be exercised. 37 This means that information referring to a known individual will be disclosed internationally (a) in circumstances regulated by the national law of the state holding that demographic information (e.g. rules governing which data may be held and exchanged, especially with regard to the gravity of offence 33 HC Deb 8 December 2015, vol. 603 cols 914-963 and HL Deb 9 December 2015, vol. 767 cols 1636 – 1648. 34 International Agreements Council, Decision of 26 July 2010 on the conclusion of the Agreement between the European Union and Iceland and Norway on the application of certain provisions of Council Decision 2008/615/JHA on the stepping up of cross- border cooperation, particularly in combating terrorism and cross- border crime and Council Decision 2008/616/JHA on the implementation of Decision 2008/615/JHA on the stepping up of cross-border cooperation, particularly in combating terrorism and cross-border crime, and the Annex thereto (2010/482/EU); and Swiss Federal Council, Coopération Prüm: le Conseil fédéral délivre un mandat de négociation, press noticed dated 13.03.2015. available at: https://www.news.admin.ch/message/index.html?lang=fr&msg-id=56539 ( accessed 14.06.15). 35 The Prüm process and filtering of scientifically unreliable ‘hits’ and criminologically unimportant matches is described in M.D. Taverne and A.P.A Broeders. The light’s at the end of the funnel!: Evaluating the effectiveness of the transnational exchange of DNA profiles between the Netherlands and other Prüm countries (Paris Legal Publishers, Zutphen:2015). The proposals for the introduction of Prüm exchanges into English Law made by Home Secretary (now Prime Minister) May can be found in Home Office, 2015 Prüm Business and Implementation Case Cm (2015) 9149 5-7 and 232-236 available at: https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/480129/prum_business_and _implementation_case.pdf ( accessed 19 July 2016). 36 Above n. 19. 37 This is indicated by an analysis in F. Santos, H. Machado and S. Silva, ‘Forensic DNA databases in European countries: is size linked to performance?’ (2013) Life Sciences, Society and Policy 9:12. It is difficult, however, especially within the text allowance for a journal article to fully describe the range of variation in national laws and a restrictive / expansionist binary division of such laws though useful is also problematic. In some countries the laws governing retention will have changed since their analysis was completed. https://www.news.admin.ch/message/index.html?lang=fr&msg-id=56539 https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/480129/prum_business_and_implementation_case.pdf https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/480129/prum_business_and_implementation_case.pdf Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 8 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 and/or the existence of a conviction) and (b) also as a result of operational judgements in both states about whether the crime is sufficiently serious to warrant the exchange of information. Such arrangements may differ under national law to take account of individual circumstances, such as the data subject’s age. 38 The Prüm legislation contains mimimum standards for data protection, but compliance is a matter for national data protection bodies and law. This is sufficiently flexible to accommodate significantly different national approaches, including the enhanced forensic biometric governance regime in England (by both the Information Commissioner and, following the Protection of Freedoms Act 2012, the appointment of a specific (forensic) Biometrics Commissioner). 39 There is a potential weakness in such arrangements as the national authorities of a transmitting state cannot know what happens to personal information from matches that have been retained in a receiving country. The classic answer would be mutual trust among EU member states, but as will be seen later even the international collection of statistics about Prüm operations is flawed and effective regulation may ultimately depend on proactive cooperation between national data supervision authorities who meet with the European Data Protection Supervisor (EDPS) and the Commission under the auspices of the Article 29 Working Party. With Brexit in mind, it is important to note that the data protection authorities of Norway, Liechtenstein and Iceland are members of that working party. 40 The EU was not particularly original in devising an approach that recognised such national autonomy. It is similar, for instance, to the rules under the Rome Statue of the International Criminal Court (ICC) (1998) for cooperation (including information sharing) with signatory states that is often seen as ’a middle ground between a vertical and horizontal model’ for state/ tribunal cooperation. 41 Given that UK accession to the Rome Statue is autonomous of its EU membership, this country’s confidence with this mode of cooperation, presumably also suggests Prüm should be an acceptable option in the event of Brexit for criminal justice cooperation more generally. The costs of Prüm implementation and the scientifc standardization required to improve the efficiency and reliability of such cooperation are not insignificant, but these will be significantly eclipsed by the national costs and benefits of forensic biometrics for purely domestic purposes. The added cost of sharing national DNA data is likely to be low. In the Netherlands the staff cost for handling and interpreting scientifically the Prüm data exchanges in the Netherlands is approximately €27 per match. 42 Prüm: The Socio-economic and Criminological Context The fate of Flight MH17 illustrates our modern globalised reality and how national resilience depends on international cooperation. The aircraft was destroyed on 17 July 2014 over Ukraine 38 See especially Articles 5, 9 and 26 of 2008/615/JHA; above n.32. 39 For the Biometric Commissioner’s powers see The Protection of Freedoms Act 2012, ss. 20-21.; For the proposed roles of the Biometric and Information Commissioners in terms of both Prüm and enhanced UK forensic biometrics governance see: Home Office, above n. 32 at 64 and 69. 40 See the entry on the EDPS website. Available at https://secure.edps.europa.eu/EDPSWEB/edps/site/mySite/Art29 (accessed 17 August 2016). 41 R. Cryer, H. Friman, D. Robinson and E. Wilmshurst, An Introduction to International Criminal Law and Procedure 2 nd ed. (CUP, Cambridge: 2010) 510. 42 See Taverne and Broeders, above n.35 at 63-64. https://secure.edps.europa.eu/EDPSWEB/edps/site/mySite/Art29 Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 9 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 when travelling from Amsterdam to Kuala Lumpur. The majority of the victims (193 out of 298 passengers and crew) were Dutch. Sixteen of the dead were British citizens, six of whom had dual nationality. Ante-mortem samples for these British victims were collected from three countries - the Netherlands, New Zealand and South Africa - in addition to the UK. 43 DNA and fingerprint experts from many nations contributed to the identification work. During its last phase, scientists from LGC Forensics (UK) were called in, alongside colleagues from Bode Cellmark Forensics (USA) and the International Commission on Missing Persons (ICMP) based in Sarajevo (Bosnia and Herzegovina), to help the Netherlands Forensics Institute accelerate the final DNA analyses of the victims’ remains. 44 Similar collaboration (including UK forensic pathologists and scientists) on another criminal act on an even greater scale serves to reinforce the point that no country - not even one as wealthy as the USA – will necessarily have sufficient national expertise to deal with the consequences of incidents on the scale of 9/11 without international assistance. As a result of being at the forefront of free trade and globalisation, the UK legal systems adapted early to the criminological consequences of the cross-border movement of citizens. The example of England and Scotland shows that this was not at the expense of their distinctive legal cultures. In Scotland, for example, the codification of criminal procedure began much earlier than in England and state law officers retain a procuratorial monopoly over the initiation of criminal proceedings. 45 More recently, the UK Parliament has effectively ceded most legislative competency in criminal justice matters, including the governance of policing within Scotland, to the Scottish Parliament. 46 There always has been and still remains, however, an almost seamless policing based on overlapping cross-border jurisdiction as well as cooperation. An English police officer’s power of arrest is exercisable in Scotland and vice versa. These reciprocal arrangements are justiciable under the law relating to arrest (including those to protect the arrestee’s rights) of the territory on which the arrest takes place and not the UK legislation that confers these reciprocal powers. 47 The demographic logic of cross-border criminal justice cooperation (both within and outside the UK) resulting from geography, colonial history and an increasingly globalised economy can be illustrated as follows:  An estimated 795,000 Scots-born citizens probably accounted in 2001 for less than 1.5% or more of the population of England and Wales, whereas some 400,000 English born citizens account for almost 9% of the population of Scotland. 48 43 J. Williams, ‘Disaster Victim Identification’ in Peplow, above n. 2 at 90-91. 44 W. Heijnen, DVI aspects of forensic investigation, plenary session iv, 7 th European Academy of Forensic Science Conference, Prague, 11 September 2015. 45 L. Harris, ‘Scotland’ in K. Ligeti (ed.), Towards a Prosecutor for the European Union, Volume 1 (Hart, Oxford: 2013) 627. 46 Scotland Act 1998 ss. 28 and 29. The same primacy of the ‘host’ member state’s national law is applied to police actions undertaken in the territory of another member state by 2008/615/JHA, for which see n. 32 at Art. 17 (2). 47 Criminal Justice and Public Order Act 1994 s. 140. 48 The latest available data for the Scottish diaspora comes from the 2001 Census, when, for those who provided information, the figure was approximately 1.5% of the population of England and Wales. See: J. Carr and L. Cavanagh, Scotland’s Diaspora and Overseas-Born Population (The Scottish Government, Edinburgh: 2009) 8 and 14. Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 10 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016  The UK global diaspora was estimated in 2010 to be equivalent to 10% (some 3.5% within the EU) of the UK resident population, compared with 5.5% in 2001. 49  Some 4% of the UK resident population was born elsewhere in the EU and approximately the same percentage of its resident population in third countries (i.e. outside the EU). Third country nationals disappear more rapidly from statistical scrutiny (as a result of naturalisation), consequently foreign born residents from third countries account for 8% of the UK resident population, but the proportion of UK citizens with global family links is much greater. 50 Genetically, non-European ancestry is estimated to extend to some 14% of the population. 51 This data, however, understates social assimilation. For example by 2011 2.3 million people were in inter-ethnic relationships, including 9% of individuals of a Pakistani background. 52  In absolute terms, UK residents are second only to German residents in being regular travellers to other EU countries (respectively, 31 million and 53 million trips in 2011), between twice or three times as many journeys as the next most travelled from countries, (France and the Netherlands) 53 .  In 2014-15, 118 million people (including UK residents) travelled to the UK, many on several occasions in that year, and approximately the same number left. (As a combined total this was approximately four times the resident population.) 54 Among the third country citizens who travelled to the UK during the year ending June 2014, for whom more detailed data is available, some 8.8 million were simply visitors (e.g. as tourists or attending business meetings) compared with 5.5 milion entering the country to study, work for a significant time or for permanent residency or asylum. 55 This significant diversity of resident population, families with multiple national heritages and increasing fluidity of location is typical of any wealthy country within the European Union. 56 49 T. Finch, H. Andrew and M. Latorre, Global Brit: Making the most of the British diaspora, 7 (IPPR, London: 2010). The 2001 estimate is taken from Carr and Cavanagh, above n.48 at 10. 50 Eurostat data (2012). Available at http://Ec.europa.eu/eurostat/statistics- explained/images/d/d8/Foreign_and_foreign- born_population_by_group_of_citizenship_and_country_of_birth_2012.png (accessed 11 February 2016). 51 This has been taken into account to calculate the risk of genetically derived errors when calculating random match probabilities for forensic DNA matches. See: The Forensic Science Regulator (2014), Guidance: Allele frequency databases and reporting guidance for the DNA (Short Tandem Repeat) profiling FSR-G-213 Issue 1. 52 E. Mian, ‘Race to the Bottom’ Prospect August 2016, 72. 53 Eurostat data (2013). Available at http://Ec.europa.eu/eurostat/statistics- explained/index.php/File:Number_of_foreign_trips_of_at_least_one_night%E2%80%99s_duration_for_person al_purposes_made_by_residents_of_EU_Member_States,_with_destination_in_the_EU_or_a_third_country,_ 2008-2011.png (accessed 11 February 2016). 54 National Audit Office, E-borders and successor programmes, HC 608 Session 2015-16, 5. 55 Home Office, Immigration statistics: January to March 2015 Available at https://www.gov.uk/government/publications/immigration-statistics-january-to-march-2015/immigration- statistics-january-to-march-2015 (accessed 22 July 2016). 56 Eurostat data (2016). Available at http://Ec.europa.eu/eurostat/statistics- explained/index.php/EU_citizenship_-_statistics_on_cross-border_activities (accessed 13.April 2016). http://ec.europa.eu/eurostat/statistics-explained/images/d/d8/Foreign_and_foreign-born_population_by_group_of_citizenship_and_country_of_birth_2012.png http://ec.europa.eu/eurostat/statistics-explained/images/d/d8/Foreign_and_foreign-born_population_by_group_of_citizenship_and_country_of_birth_2012.png http://ec.europa.eu/eurostat/statistics-explained/images/d/d8/Foreign_and_foreign-born_population_by_group_of_citizenship_and_country_of_birth_2012.png http://ec.europa.eu/eurostat/statistics-explained/index.php/File:Number_of_foreign_trips_of_at_least_one_night%E2%80%99s_duration_for_personal_purposes_made_by_residents_of_EU_Member_States,_with_destination_in_the_EU_or_a_third_country,_2008-2011.png http://ec.europa.eu/eurostat/statistics-explained/index.php/File:Number_of_foreign_trips_of_at_least_one_night%E2%80%99s_duration_for_personal_purposes_made_by_residents_of_EU_Member_States,_with_destination_in_the_EU_or_a_third_country,_2008-2011.png http://ec.europa.eu/eurostat/statistics-explained/index.php/File:Number_of_foreign_trips_of_at_least_one_night%E2%80%99s_duration_for_personal_purposes_made_by_residents_of_EU_Member_States,_with_destination_in_the_EU_or_a_third_country,_2008-2011.png http://ec.europa.eu/eurostat/statistics-explained/index.php/File:Number_of_foreign_trips_of_at_least_one_night%E2%80%99s_duration_for_personal_purposes_made_by_residents_of_EU_Member_States,_with_destination_in_the_EU_or_a_third_country,_2008-2011.png https://www.gov.uk/government/publications/immigration-statistics-january-to-march-2015/immigration-statistics-january-to-march-2015 https://www.gov.uk/government/publications/immigration-statistics-january-to-march-2015/immigration-statistics-january-to-march-2015 http://ec.europa.eu/eurostat/statistics-explained/index.php/EU_citizenship_-_statistics_on_cross-border_activities http://ec.europa.eu/eurostat/statistics-explained/index.php/EU_citizenship_-_statistics_on_cross-border_activities Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 11 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 Figure 1. Foreign nationals (% of total population) resident in EU countries (2011). Unless there is a global crisis equivalent to the 1929 Great Crash (not wholly unimaginable), it is likely that the globalised economy and the consequential locational fluidity will continue to profoundly shape the demographics and cross-border travel in the UK and neighbouring countries. North American census data supports this view. In the USA the foreign born population had exceeded the current UK figure of 8% by 1990 and by 2010 was estimated to have reached 13% of the total population. 57 The foreign-born population of Canada represented almost 21% of the total population in 2011. That is the highest such level among the G8 countries. 58 There is far less information and research, however, about the externalities (or ‘public bads’) in terms of cross-border offences or offending. Evidence about this might be judged essential for arguments about legitimate aim and capable means in a proportionality analysis, and highly significant for balancing the case for cooperation against the costs to rights of the cooperation, notably for the privacy of forensic biometric information. What is clear is that freedom of movement and migration have not affected the long-term decline in traditional (non-cyber or fraud) offences or offending. Overall crime data in the 2015 Crime Survey for England and Wales was at its lowest since it began in 1981. 59 In the twelve months ending December 2015 the number of first time entrants dealt with by English and Welsh criminal justice 57 C. J. Gibson and E. Lennon, Population Division Working Paper No. 29: Historical Census Statistics on the Foreign-Born population of The United States: 1850 To 1990, (U.S. Bureau of the Census, Washington, D.C: 1999). Available at https://www.census.gov/population/www/documentation/twps0029/twps0029.html (accessed 13 April 2016) and E. M. Grieco, Y. D. Acosta, G. P. de la Cruz, C. Gambino, T. Gryn, L. J. Larsen, E. N. Trevelyan, and N. P. Walters, Report Number: ACS-19: The Foreign-Born Population in the United States: 2010 (U.S. Bureau of the Census, Washington, D.C: 2012). Available at https://www.census.gov/library/publications/2012/acs/acs-19.html (accessed 13 April 2016). 58 Statistics Canada, Immigration and Ethnocultural Diversity in Canada (Statistics Canada, Ottawa: 2013). Available at https://www12.statcan.gc.ca/nhs-enm/2011/as-sa/99-010-x/99-010-x2011001-eng.cfm (accessed 13 April 2016). 59 Office of National Statistics, Crime in England and Wales: Year ending December 2015 5. https://www.census.gov/population/www/documentation/twps0029/twps0029.html https://www.census.gov/library/publications/2012/acs/acs-19.html https://www12.statcan.gc.ca/nhs-enm/2011/as-sa/99-010-x/99-010-x2011001-eng.cfm Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 12 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 agencies fell by 68% in the case of juveniles and 19% for adults since 2006/07 60 There are no national statistics for crimes committed by foreign citizens in England and Wales, but research by Johnson and his colleagues suggests that offending by the citizens of other EU countries accounts overall for some 1% of prosecuted offences. Their research indicates that where data exists for similar offending in other EU member states (approximately 4% of total crime in the Czech Republic, 3% in Italy, Germany and Denmark, 2.5% in the Netherlands, 1.5% in Slovakia, and less than 1% in Austria and Poland), it appears to be broadly consistent with or below the proportion of other EU nationals resident in those countries (see Figure 1 above). 61 Offences committed in the UK by the citizens of other EU states, are chiefly relatively low level acquisitive crime, particularly theft from shops. Such offending is also concentrated geographically in the south east, eastern counties and Cumbria rather than dispersed nationally. 62 This spatial concentration is consistent with other data and estimates. In London, where foreign-born people (not just from the EU) comprised 37 per cent of the population of central London and 33 per cent of the outer boroughs in 2013, it is reported that foreign citizens account for 25-30 per cent of arrests (approximately 50,000-66,000 arrests per annum) and an estimated 25 per cent of high-harm offenders (including organised crime group members and predatory sex offenders). 63 English prison data is difficult to interpret because of problems with convicted prisoner deportations, and laws and policies that encourage custody to be served in the country of nationality. In general, however, it appears to be consistent with ‘high-harm offender’ estimates. Some 9,895 foreign citizens (11.65 per cent of the total population, of which total nationals from other EU countries accounted for 4.98 per cent of that total) were held in English prisons on 31 December 2015. 6465 Although better data is needed, it is known from individual cases that generally low levels of offending and often for minor crimes by most offenders from other EU countries mask much more serious challenges for the police and prosecutors: (a) in finding the much smaller number of serious criminals among such residents and (b) in obtaining information to help assess the criminal threat that an identified individual poses. As this article at several points considers criminal justice cooperation in relation to security initiatives, it is worth noting a similar problem posed by the small number of terrorists within an estimated 1.8 million irregular EU external border crossings (compared with some 200 million authorised crossings) in 2015. 66 This is a problem identified by criminologists and policy makers since the 1990s, for example, in 1993: 60 Ministry of Justice, Criminal Justice Statistics 2015: England and Wales 34. 61 D. Johnson, A. Ludwig, B. Younger and M. McCloskey (2015) The Prüm Implementation, Evaluation and Strengthening (P.I.E.S.) of Forensic DNA Data Exchange: Northumbria University Final Report (Northumbria University, Newcastle upon Tyne, UK, 2014) (Unpublished) 6. Source of Figure 1 is Eurostat, above n. 56. 62 D. Johnson, ‘E.U. migrant criminal activity: Exploring spatial diversity and volume of criminal activity attributed to inter EU migrants in England’ (2014) 5 Applied Geography 48. 63 For sources see: Wilson above n.2 at 198 notes 15-17. 64 Ministry of Justice, Prison Population: 31 December 2015, 2016. Available at https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/495322/prison-population- 31-dEcember-2015.xlsx (accessed 8.April 2016). 65 For convicted prisoner deportation problems see: Home Affairs Committee, The work of the Immigration Directorates (Q4 2015), HC (2016–17 22) paras 89 – 93. 66 Commission, Stronger and Smarter Information Systems for Borders and Security COM (2016) 205 final 2. https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/495322/prison-population-31-december-2015.xlsx https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/495322/prison-population-31-december-2015.xlsx Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 13 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 … it may not be an exaggeration to say that criminal organizations abolished national boundaries long ago. Crossing borders is no major problem to them and the losses are marginal. They rather see the border as a handicap for police and prosecution. Crossing the border is one of the trivial precautions which are routinely taken in all kinds (including the most simple forms) of organized crime. Considering these aspects, one may conclude that national borders do not improve, but reduce public safety in Europe. 67 More recent research has described in some detail the activities of the members of travelling criminal gangs in the Netherlands. Their members systematically engage in relatively petty but high volume offending and seek to evade detection by using multiple identities and crossing borders. 68 Patterns of cross-border offending and offences will vary considerably from country to country, but in the absence of a drastic reduction in visitor and foreign worker numbers, withdrawal from the EU is highly unlikely to change this aspect of UK crime. In such circumstances, the efficient international exchange of accurate information and reliable evidence with, at least, neighbouring EU member states, is just as indispensable for UK criminal justice as traditional cooperation between this country’s internal jurisdictions. The value of forensic science for linking crimes in different jurisdictions has been illustrated by the experience of countries, such as the Netherlands, that have routinely shared forensic biometric data via Prüm for several years (Figure 2). Dutch Database: the nature of profile matched (through a scientifically validated comparison) Other member state databases: the nature of profile matched Number of matches reported to Dutch prosecutors and police Anonymous profile (trace) recovered from a crime scene The profile of a known person 3,100 Anonymous profile (trace) recovered from a crime scene Anonymous profile (trace) recovered from a crime scene 2,326 The profile of a known person Anonymous profile (trace) recovered from a crime scene 836 The profile of a known person The profile of a known person 971 Figure 2. Forensic DNA data sharing: identifications made in the Netherlands (at February 2015) 69 A match between anonymous profiles recovered from crime scenes in one or more countries may have considerable value if analysts can link such information with other crimes. This may eventually lead to the identification of a possible suspect. It can certainly be used to identify trends and spatial 67 M. Killias, ‘Will open borders result in more crime? A criminological statement’ (1993) 1 European Journal on Criminal Policy and Research 11. 68 D. Siegal, Mobile Banditry: East European and Central European Itinerant Criminal Groups in the Netherlands, Eleven International Publishing: The Hague, 2014). 69 Source: Netherlands Forensic Institute, ‘Dutch DNA database has resulted in 25,000 international matches’ 2015. Available at https://www.forensicinstitute.nl/about_nfi/news/2015/dutch-dna-database-has-resulted- in-25000-international-matches.aspx (accessed 31.May 2016). https://www.forensicinstitute.nl/about_nfi/news/2015/dutch-dna-database-has-resulted-in-25000-international-matches.aspx https://www.forensicinstitute.nl/about_nfi/news/2015/dutch-dna-database-has-resulted-in-25000-international-matches.aspx Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 14 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 features in transnational offences and offending. Used in this way, as the examples below from Belgium illustrate (see Figure 3), forensic science data analyses inform crime prevention strategies and investigative priorities at sub-regional levels. 70 Research into Belgian Prüm matches indicated, consistent with the type of offences for which forensic bioinformation can often be recovered, that 39% of such matches related to burglary, other offences included violent theft (22%), sex offences (14%) and murder or kidnapping (4%). 71 Forensic DNA is not the only forensic science discipline that - through international forensic biometric data sharing (including potentially via Prüm) - helps to give meaning to evidence recovered by investigators or unlocks access to important information from other jurisdictions about suspects. For example, fingerprint information from the mutilated remains of a suicide bomber recovered in Saint Denis was used to identify the corpse as that of a person who had been imprisoned in Belgium. 72 Latent fingerprints deposited by a person who handled or made an improvised explosive device (IED) in Afghanistan were matched with an individual arrested as a suspected illegal 70 Information for Figure 3 provided by the Nationaal Instituut voor Criminalistiek en Criminologie (NICC) / Institut National de Criminalistique et Criminologie (INCC) from work undertaken under the PIES project - The Prüm Implementation, Evaluation, and Strengthening of Forensic DNA Data Exchange (HOME/2011/ ISEC/AG/ PRUM/4000002150). For a discussion of how such data can be used at sub regional levels see: Wilson, above n.2 at 85. 71 P. Jeuniaux, ‘Building maps of transnational crimes on the basis of Prüm’, presentation at the PIES Conference held in Brussels on 29 September 2015. 72 Adam Withnall, ‘Paris attacks 'mastermind' Abdelhamid Abaaoud killed in Saint Denis raid, prosecutor confirms’ The Independent, 19 11.15. available at http://www.independent.co.uk/news/world/europe/paris- attacks-mastermind-abdelhamid-abaaoud-is-dead-following-saint-denis-raid-prosEcutor-confirms- a6740406.html (accessed 5.April 2016). http://www.independent.co.uk/news/world/europe/paris-attacks-mastermind-abdelhamid-abaaoud-is-dead-following-saint-denis-raid-prosecutor-confirms-a6740406.html http://www.independent.co.uk/news/world/europe/paris-attacks-mastermind-abdelhamid-abaaoud-is-dead-following-saint-denis-raid-prosecutor-confirms-a6740406.html http://www.independent.co.uk/news/world/europe/paris-attacks-mastermind-abdelhamid-abaaoud-is-dead-following-saint-denis-raid-prosecutor-confirms-a6740406.html Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 15 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 immigrant sometime later at a border half the world away. 73 In this respect the fingerprint identification processes used as one technique for identifying the victims of the MH17 attack comes full circle. Published research has concentrated on how forensic data exchanges helps to identify suspects and criminological trends in the country where the offence has been committed, 74 but an equally important consequence of such cooperation is that it also enables criminal justice records to be shared between jurisdictions. Bail, ‘bad character’ admissibility and sentencing decisions require knowledge of criminal careers and real-world identity. This is not only a question of criminological efficiency, or even public safety. Where prior convictions may influence guilt and punishment, the law cannot be administered equitably, if prosecutors and courts can access the pertinent records relating to their fellow citizens, but not those of other residents or visitors. Access to criminals’ back- stories can sometimes only be unlocked through sharing standardized biometric data between jurisdictions. There is a parallel EU non-biometric system for joining-up the judicial records of different member states on a case by case basis: ECRIS (European Criminal Records Information System). 75 This extends to the preventative sphere and may facilitate, subject to what is permitted under national law, the exchange of conviction information relevant to employment with children. 76 If a separate biometric database cannot be used in parallel, the use of ECRIS may have to rely solely on an ability to determine through questioning the nationality of a suspect and identify the relevant countries in which he or she may have travelled. It may also have to cope with aliases or multiple identities. Little is known about the extent of such problems, but it has been estimated that in 95% of cases where third country nationals are sentenced in EU courts, no checks have even been made for relevant criminal records in EU member states. 77 ECRIS and Prüm are complementary to each other, thus, demonstrating the importance of how EU criminal justice cooperation is evolving as a system, rather than as a series of discrete international police or security cooperation initiatives or entirely separate databases. Prüm: implementation Lessons: Scientific Standardisation International cooperation, including the co-ordinated use of research funds, is essential to facilitate progress with forensic science based international criminal justice cooperation. This was recognized 73 A. Kimery, ’DHS Testing Border Biometric Program in Hunt to Identify Terrorists’, posted 22.10.15. Available at http://inhomelandsecurity.com/dhs-testing-border-biometric-program-in-hunt-to-identify-terrorists/ ( accessed 5.April 2016). 74 For recent identification studies see: Taverne and Broeders above n. 35 and W. Bernasco, M. Lammers and K van der Beek, ‘Cross-border crime patterns unveiled by exchange of DNA profiles in the European Union’, (2015) Security Journal advance online publication, doi:10.1057/sj.2015.27. 75 See: http://ec.europa.eu/justice/criminal/european-e-justice/Ecris/index_en.htm (accessed 22 July 2016). 76 Commission, ‘Report from the Commission to the European Parliament and the Council on the implementation of Council Framework Decision 2009/315/JHA of 26 February 2009 on the organisation and content of the exchange of information extracted from criminal records between Member States’, COM(2016) 6 final 8-9. 77 Commission, ‘Impact Assessment Accompanying the proposal for a Directive of the European Parliament and of the Council amending Council Framework Decision 2009/315/JHA, as regards the exchange of information on third country nationals and as regards the European Criminal Records Information System (ECRIS), and replacing Council Decision 2009/316/JHA’, SWD(2016) 4, 8. http://inhomelandsecurity.com/dhs-testing-border-biometric-program-in-hunt-to-identify-terrorists/ http://ec.europa.eu/justice/criminal/european-e-justice/Ecris/index_en.htm Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 16 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 in the biometrics standardization aspirations of the US- Canadian ‘Smart Border Declaration’ (2001). 78 By then it was likely that there was an awareness of problem created by earlier uncoordinated national agendas during the pioneering stage of forensic DNA, with the emergence of different national multiplexes. A multiplex (marketed as a biochemistry ‘kit’) targets the forensic genetic analysis on a very small number of loci from the human genome. The analysis of only a few loci can determine whether cellular material recovered from a crime scene is identical to material donated by a known individual (‘source attribution’). DNA analysis is sometimes highly complex. Potential complications arise when small amounts and/or degraded DNA are recovered, because of the smaller genetic variation between siblings, as a result of innocent transfer, or contamination. 79 Normally, however, when sufficient and good quality cellular material is carefully recovered from a crime scene the risk of an erroneous DNA match (‘an adventitious match’) is low. Even for a technologically obsolete multiplex, such as SGM+ (based on the analysis of ten loci) in a large forensic database, such as that operating in the UK, this risk is conservatively estimated to be in the order of 1 in 1,000 million. 80 With a smaller number of loci the random probability of error is much higher, for example, with the six loci SGM multiplex the risk of error was about 1 in 50 million. 81 When national forensic science laboratories began to exchange DNA profiles there was not always a sufficient number of overlapping loci to ensure that the resulting hits/matches were scientifically valid. For example, in the Netherlands, when there were only six or seven loci in common with another country, hits/matches on the database, were respectively, 66% and 5% erroneous. 82 The strong commitment within the European political and scientific communities to make DNA sharing reliable and efficient resulted in two solutions. First, automated hits during Prüm data exchanges are monitored to identify unreliable results. If there are doubts about a hit, additional DNA testing can be undertaken to ensure that only scientifically robust matches are reported to the police or judicial authorities. 83 The latter practice is expensive and time-consuming, but such action will need to continue for many years to come. There are millions of DNA profiles - some even for national purposes (the kit improvements did more than address loci convergence problems and were intended to also improve the analysis of degraded DNA) - that have become technologically obsolescent unnecessarily early because of delayed collaborative development. Secondly, new European standard DNA loci have been introduced to ensure sufficient commonality between European multiplex. Because of a high level of global scientific cooperation, in which the 78 R. Zaiotti, ‘Practising homeland security across the Atlantic: practical learning and policy convergence in Europe and North America’ (2012) 21 European Security, 338. 79 See: P. Gill, Misleading DNA Evidence: Reasons for Miscarriages of Justice (Academic Press, London: 2014). 80 B. Bramley, ‘DNA databases’ in J. G Fraser. and R. Williams (eds.) Handbook of Forensic Science (Cullompton, Willan Publishing: 2009) 329. 81 P. Gill and T. Clayton, ‘the current status of DNA profiling in the UK’ in. Fraser and Williams, above n.80 30- 31. 82 Linda Geddes, ‘DNA super-network increases risk of mix-ups’, New Scientist, 05 September 2011 (issue 2828) . Available at https://www.newscientist.com/article/mg21128285-500-dna-super-network-increases-risk-of- mix-ups/ ( accessed 30 June 2013). 83 Above Taverne and Broeders n. 35 at 21-23. https://www.newscientist.com/article/mg21128285-500-dna-super-network-increases-risk-of-mix-ups/ https://www.newscientist.com/article/mg21128285-500-dna-super-network-increases-risk-of-mix-ups/ Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 17 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 role of the FBI has been particularly important, there is now a high level of concordance with those used by the other DNA standard setting countries: the USA and China (see Figure 4). EU research funding supported this game-changing reform, but it also benefited from parallel investment by the US and other governments in forensic DNA for internal investigative purposes. Public commitments at that time to expand the forensic use of DNA provided reassurance about potential market demand for private sector commercial investment, particularly by US bio-science. 84 As a result intellectual property in modern multiplex kits belongs mainly to such American companies and the commercial profits from manufacturing this basic criminal justice commodity are likely to accrue mainly in the USA. Figure 4: the international convergence of DNA multiplexes 85 Year Multiplex Number of markers(including, where appropriate, Amelogenin) Overlap with UK multiplex at that time Overlap with USA multiplex at that time/final four rows only by 2017 Overlap with China multiplex at that time England and Wales Scotland 1995 UK SGM 7 N/A N/A N/A 1998 USA Original CODIS 13 6 N/A N/A 1999 UK SGM+ 11 N/A 8 N/A 2010 China Sinofiler 15 9 11 N/A 2014 England and Wales DNA-17 17 N/A 11 8 10 2015 Scotland DNA-24 24 17 N/A 13 14 2017 USA CODIS core loci 20 15 20 N/A 14 At DEc. 2015 Original European Standard set (ESS/ISSOL) 7 7 7 6 6 At DEc. 2015 Current European Standard set (ESS) 12 12 12 11 7 At DEc. 2015 Prüm authorised loci (2008/616/JHA) 24 12 17 13/15 13 The UK gained some significant financial benefits from its pioneering role and investment in forensic DNA. UK government owned intellectual property (IP) rights was licensed to one of the major US biotech companies. In return for the unprotected IP, the Forensic Science Service (FSS) gained a substantial discount on its purchase of SGM+ plus kits over many years, which included, effectively, a royalty on all kits sold by that company. In return for the patent protected IP on a different kit (not an STR multiplex but used widely in both forensic science and molecular biology more generally), the FSS received an initial lump sum followed by royalties on all kits sold. 86 Standardisation is, in effect, an admission fee to criminal justice and security cooperation. It is worth noting here, in anticipation of points considered later about convergence in these areas between US and EU policy initiatives, how American commercial interests profited most from the standardisation of DNA multiplexes and, possibly, the overall emergence of forensic DNA. While little published evidence is available, it is important in the Walport context – of identifying how significant emerging technology might be exploited either directly or indirectly in the national interest - not to 84 This reflects several discussions with former bioscience company executives. 85 Table taken from Wilson, above n.2 at 87. 86 Information provided by a former senior FSS employee. It is unclear what happened to these arrangements when the FSS was closed by the first (Coalition) Cameron Administration. Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 18 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 unquestioningly accept the assumptions of market fundamentalism (or ‘neoliberalism’). 87 Successive UK governments and the EC possibly made a major error by failing to emulate, in their contribution to the development of forensic DNA, US government scientific and technical development policies. As Mazzucato has demonstrated from a wide range of examples of technological innovation fostering economic growth, it is important ’to do as the United States actually did, not just as it says it did: more State not less’. 88 Returning to the key themes of this article, the role of bio-science companies in the development of DNA multiplexes also provides a reminder that the degree of publicness of intermediate inputs into global public goods may be different to that of the final good itself. This may raise further questions about exclusivity in benefit sharing and access that may require the development of public-private partnership initiatives for the advancement of global public goods to be congruent with clear and effective public procurement and concession award laws. Prüm: Implementation Lessons: Alternative models and Enabling Effective Cooperation The multiplex issues are recorded in the academic literature relating to the development of forensic science, not least because they may have a bearing on reliability of scientific expert evidence during a trial. The legal question that needs to be noted here, however, is that having clearly satisfied the capability stage of the proportionality test, would the Prüm system satisfy the necessity test. Is there an alternative course of action capable of achieving the same aim? There is indeed an alternative and older established approach to sharing biometric forensic and other criminal justice or security information provided by Interpol. The Interpol approach differs from the Prüm model by operating as centralised database systems for fingerprints and forensic DNA. Interpol statistics are not available in the same level of detail and for extended time spans compared with Prüm, but the level of activity achieved, including for the entirely non-biometric (lost or stolen) travel documents system are given at Figure 5. 87 See, for example, J Stiglitz The Euro and its Threat to the Future of Europe (Allen Lane, London: 2016). 88 M. Mazzucato, The Entrepreneurial State (revised edition) (Anthem Press, London: 2015) at 1. Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 19 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 Figure 5: Interpol centralised database: available results 2008/10 and 2013/2014 89 Comparisons between the two systems are difficult because of two known problems with Prüm statistics. Firstly, a recorded ‘hit’ (i.e. automatically generated hit) does not necessarily indicate a scientifically valid match because there might be (but we cannot tell) insufficient common loci between the two profiles that are declared to be a hit. Secondly, as Prüm is a dispersed system with simultaneous results being obtained in two places, its ‘hit’/’match’ statistics may contain double counting. The 52,500 ‘hits’ achieved by 2012 through Prüm forensic DNA data sharing, however, can be conservatively recalculated. 90 By discounting the published cumulative total by the probably over stringent Dutch (‘hit’ to ‘match’) conversion and reporting data ratio of 33.3%, and then halving the result as a precaution against the risk of duplication, the result is approximately 17,000 matches in under four years. 91 This is a startlingly different level of activity to what is known about the Interpol system. To put the Prüm statistics in perspective, particularly in terms of the low levels of transnational offending noted previously, it is helpful to look at national and not Interpol data. The reduced Prüm total would still be equivalent to 3% of total DNA hits/matches published in 2013 for 89 The 2008/2009 data is taken from C. McCartney, R. Williams and T. Wilson (2010) The Future of Forensic Bioinformation. Available at http://www.nuffieldfoundation.org/sites/default/files/files/forensic- bioinformation-report.pdf (accessed 8.July 2015) and more recent data from the Interpol website http://www.interpol.int/ (accessed 8.July 2015). 90 Soleto Muñoz and Fiodorova, above n. 32 at 153. 91 C.P. van der Beek, Implementing Prüm’s step 1 in the Netherlands Issues and results, presentation at the PIES Conference held in Brussels on 29 September 2015. The Dutch conversation rate from an automated ‘hit’ to a verified ‘match’ is conservative because the Database Custodian either eliminates scientifically valid results or does not attempt to validate hits when information is unlikely to be of interest to prosecutors. http://www.nuffieldfoundation.org/sites/default/files/files/forensic-bioinformation-report.pdf http://www.nuffieldfoundation.org/sites/default/files/files/forensic-bioinformation-report.pdf http://www.interpol.int/ Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 20 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 all the 26 original Prüm member states, or more matches than the total number of national forensic DNA matches ever achieved in all but eight of those countries. 92 The comparative greater success of the Prüm technical model is reinforced by the data for fingerprint matches and vehicle related information responses. In 2014 the annual totals were, respectively, more than 6,000 and 2 million, by when (unadjusted for scientific validity or duplication) DNA ‘hits’ had exceeded 73,000. 93 Further perspective can be gained by looking at ‘major project’ delivery failure rates, especially where multiple IT interfaces coincide with varying degrees of legal complexity. Such comparisons are bound to some degree to be approximate, but the UK e-borders programme, designed to improve border control faced similar implementation challenges to Prüm:  It required more than 600 air, ferry and rail carriers to supply data about people they are bringing in and out of the UK, and around 30 UK government agencies were also to supply data on persons of interest. All three Prüm data sources together require three times that number of international interfaces and, particularly for fingerprints, significant inter-agency and regional connectivity within member states, and by 2014 (Year 6) had achieved over 750 international connections.  It was also suggested that a lack of clarity within UK government and among its contractors about what was legal under European law further exacerbated the difficult relationships with carriers. As, noted earlier, the Prüm system provides an international exchange framework, but with considerable autonomy in the national laws relating to forensic bioinformation. The e-borders project was initiated in 2003, much earlier than Prüm, and was intended to be completed in 2011. The UK Government signed a contract In November 2007 with Raytheon, a US- based technology and defence company, to implement the programme, but this was terminated in 2010. Following a protracted legal dispute, which was settled out of court in 2015, it was estimated that successive governments had spent ‘at least’ £830 million between 2003 and 2015 on the e- borders programme and its successors. The programme was judged by the National Audit office to have successfully delivered some valuable new capabilities, but to have failed to deliver the programme’s objectives in full. 94 To reach a balanced view of the Prüm delivery model and the e-borders project, context is all important: 92 ENSFI forensic DNA database statistics published on 4.11.2013, but no longer publicly accessible on the ENSFI website. 93 General Secretariat of the Council, ‘Council Decision 2008/615/JHA of 23 June 2008 on the stepping up of cross-border cooperation, particularly in combating terrorism and cross-border-crime, Council Decision 2008/616/JHA of 23 June 2008 on the implementation of Council Decision 2008/615/JHA of 23 June 2008 on the stepping up of cross-border cooperation, particularly in combating terrorism and cross-border-crime ("Prüm Decisions") statistics and reports on automated data exchange for 2014’. 94 National Audit Office, above n.54, paras 8 and 14. Exact comparisons cannot be made, but by Year 7 (2010, with latest/2015 data in parenthesis) e-borders had achieved the following information flows: 50/(100)% outbound passports and 50/(80)% inbound passport, but unknown/(20)% for the intelligence ‘richer’ booking data (paras 1.15-1.16). Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 21 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 … IT projects in general, and large public IT projects in particular, indeed tend to fail. IT projects display an alarming rate of failure in terms of both schedule and cost overruns. Perhaps even more severely, large projects have a tendency not to deliver the promised value, and some are abandoned with a huge net loss, having failed to realize any value at all. Large scale public IT projects are typically triggered by policy reform and consequently highly visible in the media as taxpayer’s money is on the line. 95 It is also important to recognize, commonly misplaced criticism of the activities of states and supra- national bodies, that in many of the cases where the public sector ‘failed’, it was trying to do something much more difficult than what many private businesses do…’ 96 Prüm is not solely a European achievement. It benefited from the policy of successive US administrations that made a crucial unilateral contribution to international cooperation, by sharing without charge (except for installation team costs) FBI CODIS (Combined DNA Index System) software. This is used in over 50 countries globally to identify matches among DNA profiles, both nationally and also in Prüm countries for international sharing. 97 Such dependence on USA technology has not come without technical and scientific problems. As indicated in Figure 4, US multiplex do not rely on Amelogenin to determine gender for source attribution purposes. This can cause problems within Europe. Gender mismatches are ignored and amelogenin is included in the automatic counting of the minimum number matching loci. 98 Although not on the same scale as the loci overlap problem, this will result in some additional erroneous automated hits, thus continuing to add to the cost of the monitoring and validation processes described earlier. This disadvantage, however, is probably outweighed by the benefits of building the Prüm system around a single and proven set of DNA comparison software. As the new generation of increased loci multiplex profiles become more common it is likely to cease to be a significant problem for Prüm exchanges. As indicated above, despite the technical success of the Prüm model, achieving full connectivity has been slow. By the end of 2014 (Year 6) it had reached 29 per cent for fingerprints, 36 per cent for DNA and 55 per cent for vehicle/driver registration data. 99 This is probably explained by the time required for settling the national legislation needed to govern the operation of the Prüm system in each member state, the need sometimes to co-ordinate the cooperation of many different national agencies that will share data and, in the case of fingerprints, intra-national database interfaces between regional and specialist data collections. Something of the process can be appreciated from Prüm implementation processes in Poland. This is presented in Figure 6 as three distinct and consecutive cycles of activity. 95 K. Holgeid and M. Thompson A Reflection on Why Large Public Projects Fail 11 Available at https://www.jbs.cam.ac.uk/fileadmin/user_upload/programmes/emba/downloads/A_ReflEction_on_Why_Lar ge_Public_IT_ProjEcts_Fail_-_Kjetil__Mark_Thompson_s_chapter.pdf (accessed 7 April 2016). 96 M. Mazzucato, above n. 87 at 25. 97 Federal Bureau of Investigation, ‘CODIS Brochure’. Available at https://www.fbi.gov/about-us/lab/biometric- analysis/codis/codis_brochure (accessed 14 July 2016). 98 C.P van der Beek, The Prüm framework on DNA data exchange Present status and remaining issues, presentation at the PIES Conference held in Brussels on 29 September 2015. 99 General Secretariat, above n. 92. https://www.jbs.cam.ac.uk/fileadmin/user_upload/programmes/emba/downloads/A_Reflection_on_Why_Large_Public_IT_Projects_Fail_-_Kjetil__Mark_Thompson_s_chapter.pdf https://www.jbs.cam.ac.uk/fileadmin/user_upload/programmes/emba/downloads/A_Reflection_on_Why_Large_Public_IT_Projects_Fail_-_Kjetil__Mark_Thompson_s_chapter.pdf https://www.fbi.gov/about-us/lab/biometric-analysis/codis/codis_brochure https://www.fbi.gov/about-us/lab/biometric-analysis/codis/codis_brochure Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 22 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 Figure 6: The Prüm implementation cycle in Poland 100 (a) Transposition/legislative implementation cycle [2005] to 2012 (b) Technical implementation cycle 2011 to 2015 Relevant existing legislation prior to Prüm (June 2008):  The Police Act (1990)  The Polish Constitution (1997)  The Code of Criminal Procedure (1997)  The Protection of Personal Data Act (1997) Legislative changes made to create the legal framework that governs the technical facilitation of Prüm exchanges:  Order no 1565 of the Police Commander in Chief dated 29 December 2005 [DNA only, and appears to have been issued in anticipation of Prüm]  The Act for the Exchange of Information with the Law Enforcement Authorities of the Member States of the European Union (2011)  The Ordinance of the Minister of Internal Affairs (2012) Other legislative changes relevant to Prüm exchanges:  The Act on Proceedings against Persons with Mental Disorders…(2013) Other legislative changes relevant to the probative significance of forensic bioinformation in Poland:  Amendments to the Code of Criminal Procedure (2013 & 2015) Assessment EU Prüm member states’ experts Initiation of routine data sharing By early 2016, sharing data VRD 28-29 Nov 2011 Jan 2012 17 countries DNA 23-25 Oct 2012 Jan 2013 17 countries Fingerprints 24-26 Nov 2014 Nov 2015 8 countries (c) Operational initiation /match filtering cycle 2012 onwards In was recognized that a decision making process needed to be initiated to determine which verified matches should be prioritized (alternatively which cases to ‘filter out for no immediate action) for further action. Relevant factors, in addition to criminologically determined priorities, such as the seriousness of the offence, will include the avoidance of potential legal inhibitors to further investigation or prosecution. For example, it will be important to have regard to date on which crimes were committed in order to avoid investigations/proceedings becoming time barred should the verified match result in strong case for prosecuting the suspected person/suspect. While the Prüm transposition and implementation processes may have been complicated and complex in many member states, Prüm implementation will have rarely taken place in a legislative or criminal justice policy vacuum. Again, taking Poland as an example and confining the observations to directly relevant legislation, concurrently with the Prüm work there were major amendments in 2013 and 2015 to the Code of Criminal Procedure. Under the Polish Constitution this regulates criminal procedure in some detail. 101 .These changes culminated in July 2015 with a switch to a more adversarial approach that appears to have created significant challenges for prosecutors, the police and the forensic science community. 102 The Code of Criminal Procedure also governs the collection and use of forensic biometric data, including uploading it to a national database. Further new legislation (The Act on Proceedings against Persons with Mental disorders….) involving forensic biometrics dealing, inter alia, with, unidentified bodies and persons who attempt to conceal their 100 The author is grateful to Professor zw. dr hab C. Kulesza and Dr. D. Kużelewski, Faculty of law, University of Bialystok for their detailed and patient introduction to the relevant Polish criminal justice legislation at a UKPFE workshop held in Warsaw on 23.10.2014 and later an officer from the International Information Exchange Department, International Police Cooperation Bureau, Police National HQ at the United Kingdom Prüm Fingerprint Evaluation (UKPFE) Project, End of Project Conference, The Hague, 14-15.01. 2016. Any subsequent error or omission is solely attributable to the author. 101 C. Nowak and S. Steinborn, ‘Poland’ in K. Ligeti (ed.), Towards a Prosecutor for the European Union, Volume 1: A comparative Analysis (Hart, Oxford: 2013) at 498-539. 102 For a brief synopsis of the changes see: M. Mączka-Pacholak, Guest Post: New Polish Criminal Procedure Code, 1 July 2015,< https://www.fairtrials.org/press/guest-post-new-polish-criminal-procedure-code/ > accessed 31 March 2016. The author was able to discuss these changes directly with legal academics, a prosecutor and forensic scientists on three research visits to Poland. https://www.fairtrials.org/press/guest-post-new-polish-criminal-procedure-code/ Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 23 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 identity will also have placed extra demands on forensic database management and staff during the Prüm implementation period. 103 Discussion: The Potential Advantages of the Prüm Model and will it be able to Withstand Shocks? Prüm’s technical architecture and the project implementation strategies developed by the Commission, other EU institutions and member states, even with 2014 levels of connectivity, appear to reflect successful decision making and implementation management for a project of this type. At first sight, there would seem little need to distinguish between Prüm design and implementation as an exemplar for the delivery of international criminal justice cooperation as an intermediate input into global public goods and, in its legal structure, a model likely to satisfy the capability and necessity stages of a proportionality test. Such a view could be mistaken. It should not be overlooked that EU institutions have also successfully introduced high volume central databases for external border control purposes: the Schengen Information System (SIS), the VISA Information System (VIS) and the asylum applicants and third country irregular entrants records (EURODAC). All of these contain and make use of forensic biometric data and are accessible to member states for criminal justice and security purposes. There is a distinction, however, that may be relevant to the socio- cultural issues identified by Loader and Walker. All the EU centralised systems, with the exception of SIS, hold data exclusively about third country nationals, though potentially, post-Brexit, also UK citizens. A further important question is whether the Prüm decentralised model is preferable from a legal human rights, and data protection perspective? Soleto Muñoz and Fiodorova, after noting the ‘huge difference’ in the greater volume of forensic biometric exchanges facilitated by Prüm compared with the Interpol system, even at the date of their research (completed in July 2013), did not attribute this to technical choices and implementation skills. Instead, they suggested that better national control over the data under the Prüm System, confidence in data protection, a tendency to search for information within the Schengen area first and above all mutual trust between EU countries compared with the arrangements for and context in which the Interpol system operates might explain these differences. 104 It should perhaps be emphasised that, as far as their first point is concerned, Prüm operations offer much more transparency to national data supervisory authorities and will directly reflect how each state has chosen to make use of the accepted wide margin of appreciation over the use forensic bioinformation. In these respects there are qualitative and constitutional reasons in favour of the Prüm model. This view is reinforced by a potentially powerful socio-cultural resonance, especially in a country like the UK that is cautious about ceding sovereignty or the control of aspects its international activities to supra-national bodies, such as Interpol, that are bureaucratically managed, lack transparency and are not democratically accountable. The maximum degree of legal are autonomy, reserved governance and interface with suspect rights under the Prüm model of cooperation, is comfortably like the cross-jurisdictional relationship described in the second part of this article between England and Scotland and accepted by the UK with the Rome Statue. However, it is important to stress that their other points about the success of 103 The Act of 22 November 2013 on Proceedings against Persons with Mental Disorders Posing a Threat to the Life, Health or Sexual Freedom of other Persons…. . 104 Soleto Muñoz and Fiodorova, above n.32 at 153. Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 24 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 the Prüm model reflect what was suggested earlier about EU criminal justice stem from how it has developed as a system and not a series of discrete projects. It is possible to go further and suggest that perhaps another socio-cultural factor may also be relevant for understanding the Prüm project. This suggestion is based on extended and frequent observations of the key players in Prüm implementation. 105 Key experts from Europol, Eurojust, the Netherlands Forensic Institute (NFI) and the German Federal Criminal Police Office (BKA), together with colleagues from highly proactive member states, especially Austria, formed a small and, as far as other member states have experienced, inclusive community to resolve implementation problems. This observation is consistent with global public goods research - albeit concerned with a different stage in the policy cycle – about the importance for national delegations to intergovernmental negotiations to be able to ensure continuity, interdisciplinary knowledge and skills within the team, together with the ability to develop and exploit an institutional memory. 106 It also has some similarities to what Zaiotti has described as practical learning after analysing the personal interactions behind some of the convergence between EU and US security policies. 107 These arguments do not address an important political consideration: equity in the distribution of ‘publicness’ in the distribution of net benefits (e.g. in the allocation of input costs betweeen richer and poorer countries and decision making). 108 In terms of the specific context of this article, does the Prüm legislation oblige states of (migratory) origin to undertake the cost of databasing criminal justice information for the benefit of destination states? In otherwords, does it force the internalization of externalities? Certainly during the initial years of Prüm concerns were expressed in Portugal about how its promotion by more influential member states might distort criminal justice expenditure priorities in that country. 109 At a more extreme level of influence, academic discourse about international security and policing cooperation warns of the potential risk of subtle ‘re- colonisation’? 110 There is certainly an element of the internalization of externalities in Prüm and, as in all economic and political relationships with significantly asymmetrical distributions of influence. Various funding models have been developed in recognition of these issues. For example, ‘a common pool’ approach based on assessed contributions reflecting national wealth and vulnerability. 111 Alternatively, 105 These observations are derived from periods as a senior UK civil servant (2003-5) and a researcher (2006- 2010 and 2012-16). 106 P Chasek and L Rajamani, ‘Steps Toward Enhanced Parity: Negotiating Capacity and Strategies of Developing Countries’ in Kaul et al., above n.4 at 245-262. 107 Zaiotti, above n.78 at 328-346. 108 I. Kaul, P. Conceição, K.Le Goulven and R.U. Mendoza, ‘How to improve the Provision of Global Public Goods’ in Kaul et al, above n.4 at 21-58. 109 C. I. McCartney, T. J. Wilson and R. Williams, ‘Transnational Exchange of Forensic DNA: Viability, Legitimacy, and Acceptability’ (2011) 17 Eur J Crim Policy Res 309; and H. Machado and S. Silva ‘Portuguese forensic DNA database’ in R. Hindmarsh and B. Prainsack (eds), Genetic Suspects: Global Governance of Forensic DNA Profiling and Databasing (CUP: Cambridge MA, 2011) 233-234; and H. Machado and S. Silva ‘Trust, morality and altruism in the donation of biological material: the case of Portugal’ (2009) 28 New Genetics and Society 103–104. 110 M. den Boer, review: ‘Crafting trans-national policing. Police capacity building and global policing reform’ (see above n. 6) (2009) 19 Policing and Society, 325-328. 111 Sandler, above n.30 at 194-216. Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 25 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 internalizing states might directly bear modest costs, thus acting like consumers exercising solidarity following normative reflection about climate change 112 . Prüm has been implemented under what appears to be a reasonable hybrid model with ‘significant financial and technical support’ from the Commision or other European instituions and followed by additional low operational costs for national criminal justice systems that aspire to have access to the investigative and probative power of forensic science. 113 There are clear mutual advantages to be gained from criminal justice cooperation generally, as indicated, for example, in the Scott-Baker Review of Extradition: … extradition operates on the basis of mutual benefit and obligations. Given the ease of movement of people throughout the world, the United Kingdom needs the help of the international community to fight serious crime within its borders, just as much as other states need the assistance of the United Kingdom to deal with crime affecting their interests. 114 Hence, the European Arrest Warrant (EAW) was defended by Prime Minister (then Home Secretary) May, in a move foreshadowing her advocacy of Prüm, even against fierce criticism from Eurosceptics in her own party. 115 Beyond such instrumental considerations, however, the deontological and retributive significance of the criminal law distinguishes it from administrative regulation. 116 Such considerations are evident in the extra-territorial jurisdictional powers of English criminal courts for a limited number of serious crimes. These offences range from murder or manslaughter (since 1861) to offences under the Bribery Act 2010. This may sometimes result in powerful congruence with global public goods, such as good governance. Indeed, the universal jurisdiction given to English courts over acts of torture – irrespective of the nationality of perpetrator and victim or location of the offence – goes so far as to transcend normal conceptions of criminal jurisdiction in the protection of universal human rights. 117 The shock (in the sense used in the econcomic and political sciences), from the number of deaths attributable to terrorist crimes in France (234 from 7 January 2015 to 14 July 2016 118 ), is testing the robustness of such congruence between legal doctrine, particularly on human rights, and global public goods. Such events are reinforcing the securitization trajectory of the EU criminal justice cooperation policy making agenda (or alternatively blurring the distinction between criminal justice cooperation and security as global public goods). Since 9/11 cooperation between the USA and the EU, and in North America cooperation between the USA and Canada with, sometimes, also Mexico 112 For example, consumers may be willing to internalize the externalities of energy production (health, climate change and energy insecurity) by the payment of higher prices for green energy production. See A. Longoa, A. Markandya and M Petrucci, ‘The internalization of externalities in the production of electricity: Willingness to pay for the attributes of a policy for renewable energy’ (2008) 67 Ecological Economics 140-152. 113 Commission,’Stronger and Smarter Information Systems for Borders and Security’ COM (2016) 205, 9. 114 A Review of the United Kingdom’s Extradition Arrangements (Scott Baker Review) Home Office, London: 2011), 10. 115 HC Deb, 10 July 2014 vol 584, cols 486-491 116 See, for example, P. Roberts and A. Zuckerman, Criminal Evidence, 2nd edn (OUP: Oxford, 2010) 9-14. 117 s. 134 of the Criminal Justice Act 1988; see R.A. Duff, Answering for Crime: Responsibility and Liability in the Criminal Law (Hart: Oxford, 2007) 54-56. 118 ‘Deaths in terror attacks in Fance linked to Islamists’ The New European, July 22-28 2016, 9. Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 26 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 has seen the emergence of overlapping perimeter security for North America and the EU on a quasi- Schengen shared intelligence model, though for political reasons this is often described as ‘zones of confidence’. 119 Some of the North American discussions, initially sparked by concerns about physical safety, have also appear to have been intermittently extended to cover a wider globalisation induced agenda of economic security, environmental protection, and food and product safety. 120 This is an area where congruence between security as a global public good and legal doctrine have already been severly strained. Reactions to US practices, such as extraordinary rendition and secret detention facilities, mass surveillance activities and discrimination (eg in the selective application of the visa waiver programme) have divided European instituions. The EU-US Passenger Name Record (PNR) agreement is good example of such turbulence. The first agreement (2004) was invalidated by the ECJ. Negotiations about a revised (2007) PNR agreement struggled and were only finally supported by the European Parliament in 2010. Major questions about an asymmetrical relationship remain, however, with some American criticism of the European stance on data protection when the huge US intelligence resources that Europeans could not expect to match, also defends Europe. 121 Some (even transatlantic) observations suggest that European officials have through forging close and practically orientated working relationships come to ‘tame’ some of the US unilateralist tendencies. 122 The entering into force of the EU-US 'Umbrella Agreement' on data exchanges for law enforcement was made dependent on the passage of US legislation in 2016 to enable EU citizens to bring civil actions under the US 1974 Privacy Act against the relevant US government agencies for unlawful disclosures of law enforcement records transferred to the USA. While, when reacting to European political pressures, the Commission has indicated that the Paris and Brussels (2015-16) terrorist crimes require the urgent completion of full connectivity for data systems such as Prüm and improved database interoperability for the police and border guards of all data held through single search interfaces with, thus, potentially biometric identification across all EU databases. This has been balanced by an emphasis on human rights and data protection. 123 It would be unwise to underestimate the greater influence of the USA in its clearly asymmetrical relationship with the EU and the political impact on Europe of shocks from terrorist crime. Such circumstances give traction to policy convergence, as can be seen, for example, in the eventual EU-wide PNR with mandatory information about flights into and outside the EU, and discretionary powers for similar data exchanges on intra-EU travel. 124 This proposal was rejected in 2013 by the European Parliament (on grounds of ‘necessity and proportionality’), but following the first 2015 terrorist murders in Paris, it called for such a directive to be adopted by the end of that year. 125 119 Above n.78 at 341. 120 Ibid. at 339. 121 Parliament, ‘EU-US cooperation in Justice and Home Affairs – an overview’, PE (2016) 580.892 122 Above n. 78 at 331 and 338. 123 Commission, ‘Stronger and Smarter Information Systems for Borders and Security’ COM (2016) 205 final 3- 4, 8 and 11. 124 Directive 2016/681 of the European Parliament and of the Council of 27 April 2016 on the use of passenger name record (PNR) data for the prevention, detection, investigation and prosecution of terrorist offences and serious crime. 125 Parliament, Completing the adoption of an EU PNR Directive, PE (2016) 580.8 86. Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 27 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 Against such pressures the opportunity provided by judicial review for reflection and reconsideration of security and criminal justice cooperation measures is clearly essential. The CJEU has reserved to itself the power to invalidate a Commission finding that a third country arrangement for the transfer of personal data is lawful. Its case law, however has established the justiciability of challenges to the lawfulness of such arrangements, including the proportionality of security cooperation with the USA, before national data protection authorities and courts. 126 This is the final example in this article of the importance of congruence between global public goods and legal doctrine. Exceptional and threatening circumstances may reduce obstacles to policy convergence, particularly in an asymmetrical relationship, reducing the normal power of both socio-legal inhibitors and muffling the more clearly articulated political arguments about political and legal autonomy. Such circumstances also serve as a reminder about the ultimate public good: wise government. This relies on the third branch of government, the courts, undertaking their role in what should be a tripartite system of checks and balances. If democracy is to survive crises in an age of media fed anxieties, it is not simply a matter of majoritarian will. Its foundations are an endowment based on the experience of generations of voters, politicians, policy makers, legislators and jurists that is known as the rule of law and without which the public goods that matter will be scantily supplied. Conclusions This article has sought to examine the sharing of forensic bioninformation in order to answer a series of questions. In the author’s view several can be dealt with very briefly. Prüm is an effective model as an intermediate input into the production of a global public good(s). This stems from a number of reasons, in particular the way that it respects national political and legal autonmy over the regulation and use of sensitive personal data in a manner that can be effectively regulated by national courts. Also the governance of the system’s operation remains at a national level. Though this may need to be reinforced by international cooperation among national data protection supervisers. It is clearly unsatisfactory, however, that the published statistics for DNA sharing are probably exaggerated by duplication and do not distinguish between automated (not necessary valid) hits and scientifically validated matches. Compared with interpol’s centralised approach and mindful of the problems of major IT project delivery, Prüm implementation appears to have been highly successful. This may be partly a matter of choice over the decision of a decentralised system, but it also owes some of this success to mutual confidence in the European Union’s legal and insitutional structure, of which member state interelationships are a key element, as well as the form that the working relationships have taken among key experts from European insitutions and member states who cooperated to ensure its success. Clearly, achieving full connectivity is now important and the Commision has rightly proposed that this should be as a priority in order to make criminal justice and security cooperation more effective at a time of frequent and serious terrorist crimes. Having considered the consequences for the increasing securitisation of criminal justice cooperation and in particular growing EU-US policy policy convergence, the stability of the Prüm model can be seen to depend on the checks and balances of the European insitutions and their relationship with 126 Case C-362/14 Maximillian Schrems v Data Protection Commissioner [2015] ECLI:EU:C: 650. Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 28 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 national instituons. In this respect congruence between the global public good objects that Prüm serves and legal doctrine is important and compared with interpol or bilateral cooperation offer the vital safeguards of justiciability before national courts, CJEU and ECtHR. On the debit side doubts have been raised about whether the influence of market fundamentalism within the UK may have possibly resulted in little or insufficient long-term benefit for the UK national interst from its pioneering role in the forensic use of DNA. It is suggested, in terms of the Walport remit for identifying how significant emerging technology might be exploited either directly or indirectly for this purpose, that policy makers may need to understand better how US technological innovation and economic growth rely on the state Finally, given the Walport focus of this special issue, what are the implications of the EU Referendum results for UK law and policy making towards this model of international criminal justice cooperation? At the time of writing (August 2016) and the immense uncertainty over (a) what Brexit might mean and, whatever that is, (b) whether it is achievable in a rational manner, this is clearly a more difficult question. Criminal justice and security need to be broadly treated in common and such cooperation should not be approached as simply a subordinate question to this country’s future relationship with the European Union. An attempt has been made in this article to explain how the UK is too integrated within a globalised economy not to be affected by the negative spillovers of transnational crime and offending. Its physical borders and greater bureaucratic impediments to movement, therefore, are unlikely to have a significant impact on the comparatively small number of internationally mobile criminals who have committed serious crimes or who pose grave threats. A clear example of how the lack of mandatory cooperational obligations (on the EU model) can frustrate justice is the ’wall of protection’ provided by Russia for the two suspects named by Sir Robert Owen in his report into the death of Alexander Litvinenko. 127 . The conclusions in the inquiry report about the fact of and responsibility for the murder of Mr Litvinenko (paras 10.10 - 10.13) are expressed in terms used by the Inquiry Chairman to indicate his personal judgement to the criminal standard of proof (see para 2.20). The UK lost some of its global influence on 23 rd June 2016. With securitization increasing pressure for EU-US convergence on crimimal justice and security issues, there will be no scope (even if there were the time and resources to pursue them) for UK bespoke solutions. Moreover, it is possible to discern, even in North America, a growing appetite for zones of security and/or criminal justice cooperation on an integrated Schenghen model; and , possibly, picking up another Walport theme, eventually environmental and consumer protection goods regulation. International relationships among G8 countries and their immediate neighbours appear to be moving away from shopping lists with access to a database here or mutual assistance there. Physically and legally the UK is and will remain in the EU sphere of influence in such matters and policy makers need to carefully study the nature of the relationships achieved in this respect by Prüm members such as Iceland and Norway. Obviously such analyses must be updated to take account of some of the more recent developments noted in this article, such as the recently conceded rights to EU citizens to be able to litigate against 127 The Litvinenko Inquiry: Report into the death of Alexander Litvinenko, HC (2015-16) 695, para 9.179 Accepted version, as corrected at proof stage and with final funding statement. 29 ©T.J. Wilson, 2016 US government agencies for the misuse of criminal justice or security data sharing. Serious thought also needs to be given to possible socio-cultural reactions, if the price of a summer holiday in Spain for a British citizen might in the future be the retention of sensitive personal information on a central EU database. Particularly where that data could be used by a policeman or border guard with access to any EU criminal justice or security system, and without any UK national governance of the data or the use of such information being justiciable in this country’s courts. Acknowledgement The author wishes to thank colleagues and criminal justice professionals at a Sage-sponsored seminar for their helpful comments and questions about an earlier draft of this article. Other more specific acknowledgements are to be found in the footnotes. Declaration of Conflicting Interests The author(s) declared no potential conflicts of interest with respect to the research, authorship, and/or publication of this article. Funding The author(s) disclosed receipt of the following financial support for the research, authorship, and/or publication of this article: Research on which this article is based was undertaken as a result of participation in two projects: The Prüm Implementation, Evaluation, and Strengthening of Forensic DNA Data Exchange (PIES) and The United Kingdom Prüm Fingerprint Evaluation (UKPFE). Both projects were supported by the ISEC Programme Prevention of and Fight Against Crime of the Directorate General Home Affairs of the European Commission (project numbers: HOME/2011/ISEC/AG/PRUM/4000002150 and HOME/2012/ISEC/AG/4000004396). Responsibility for the content of this article lies solely with the author. The European Commission is not responsible for the contents of this article or any views expressed herein. work_haqux5lcxzbppcl3kll6ojoenu ---- CY416B/Elster-FM.tex P1: JZP 0521839696agg.xml CY416B/Elster 0 521 83969 6 June 16, 2004 15:27 Closing the Books Transitional Justice in Historical Perspective JON ELSTER Columbia University iii P1: JZP 0521839696agg.xml CY416B/Elster 0 521 83969 6 June 16, 2004 15:27 published by the press syndicate of the university of cambridge The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge, United Kingdom cambridge university press The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge cb2 2ru, uk 40 West 20th Street, New York, ny 10011-4211, usa 477 Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, vic 3207, Australia Ruiz de Alarcón 13, 28014 Madrid, Spain Dock House, The Waterfront, Cape Town 8001, South Africa http://www.cambridge.org C© Jon Elster 2004 This book is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press. First published 2004 Printed in the United States of America Typeface Sabon 10/13 pt. System LATEX 2ε [tb] A catalog record for this book is available from the British Library. Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Elster, Jon, 1940– Closing the books : transitional justice in historical perspective / Jon Elster. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references. isbn 0-521-83969-6 – isbn 0-521-54854-3 (pb.) 1. Political crimes and offenses. 2. Justice and politics. 3. Ex post facto laws. 4. Revolutions. 5. Restorative justice i. Title. k5250.e44 2004 303.6′6–dc22 2004043581 isbn 0 521 83969 6 hardback isbn 0 521 54854 3 paperback iv P1: JZP 0521839696agg.xml CY416B/Elster 0 521 83969 6 June 16, 2004 15:27 Contents Preface and Acknowledgments page ix part i the universe of transitional justice 1 1 Athens in 411 and 403 b.c. 3 2 The French Restorations in 1814 and 1815 24 3 The Larger Universe of Cases 47 part ii analytics of transitional justice 77 4 The Structure of Transitional Justice 79 5 Wrongdoers 136 6 Victims 166 7 Constraints 188 8 Emotions 216 9 Politics 245 References 273 Index 289 vii P1: KIC/IRP 0521839696agg.xml CY416B/Elster 0 521 83969 6 June 16, 2004 17:35 part i THE UNIVERSE OF TRANSITIONAL JUSTICE Transitional justice is made up of the processes of trials, purges, and reparations that take place after the transition from one political regime to another. A fuller characterization is provided in Chapter 4. The task of the present book is, first, to describe the variety of cases of transitional justice and, second, to propose an analytical framework that can help us explain the variations among the cases. Part I is devoted to presentation of the cases. In the first two chapters I describe several historical examples in some detail. Chapter 1 describes the processes of transitional justice that occurred in the wake of the restorations of Athenian democracy in 411 and then again in 403 b.c. In Chapter 2, I discuss the measures of retribution and reparation that took place in France after the two Restorations of the Bourbon monarchy in 1814 and 1815. Chapter 3 is a more compact survey of transitional justice in other cases, mainly transitions to democracy in the twentieth century. There are several reasons that I single out the Athenian and French episodes for a fuller discussion than what I provide for other cases. First, they will be less known to most readers than the more recent cases. Second, they show that transitional justice is not limited to modern regimes nor to democratic regimes. Third, both cases show exceptionally clearly that in transitional justice, nations can learn from experience. The measures taken after the second restoration of Athenian democracy were shaped by what was perceived as excessive severity in the first. Conversely, tran- sitional justice after the Second French Restoration was shaped by the perceived failure to strike hard enough in the First. In our century, too, transitional justice can be shaped by the memory of earlier transitions, the most striking instance being the three German transitions of the twentieth 1 P1: KIC/IRP 0521839696agg.xml CY416B/Elster 0 521 83969 6 June 16, 2004 17:35 2 The Universe of Transitional Justice century: after World War I, after World War II, and after reunification in 1990. On each of the last two occasions, many of those who wanted to hold the outgoing regime to account were adamant that they would not repeat the mistakes that had been made the previous time.1 In Belgium, the desire to hold speedy trials of collaborators after World War II was shaped in part by the memory of the failure to prosecute those who had collaborated with the Germans during World War I (see Chapter 8). 1 On the back cover of a book documenting the lack of denazification of the West German judiciary (Friedrich 1998), a high judge and a law professor both draw the lesson that the same error must not be repeated in dealing with the East German judiciary. For a criticism of this argument, see Rottleuthner (1994). For the relation between 1918 and 1945, see Chapter 7. P1: KIC/IRP 0521839696agg.xml CY416B/Elster 0 521 83969 6 June 16, 2004 17:35 1 Athens in 411 and 403 B.C. i. introduction Democratic transitional justice is almost as old as democracy itself. In 411 b.c. and then again in 404–403 b.c., the Athenians saw the over- throw of democracy by an oligarchy, followed by defeat of the oligarchs and restoration of democracy.1 In each case, the return to democracy went together with retributive measures against the oligarchs. In 403, the Athenians also took steps toward restitution of property that had been confiscated by the oligarchic regime. The next episode of transitional justice occurred more than two thousand years later, in the English Restoration. The Athenians had two episodes of transitional justice that followed closely upon each other. It seems likely that after the first episode some learning took place, shaping the next occurrence. After the collapse of the first oligarchy in 411, the Athenians restored the pre-oligarchic democ- racy, carried out harsh retribution, and enacted new laws to deter future oligarchs from trying to take power. What they did not do was to attack the root causes of the oligarchic coup. In 403, the returning democrats reacted differently. On the one hand, they enacted constitutional changes to eliminate features that had brought democracy into disrepute. On the other hand, they pulled their punches in dealing with the oligarchs, 1 In the following I rely heavily on Ostwald (1986). My indebtedness to Hansen (1991) will also be obvious. The most recent monograph on the transition in 403 is Loening (1987). Although many of the stark statements in the text ignore important controversies in the scholarly literature, I do not think this affects the substance of the argument, as summarized toward the end. 3 P1: KIC/IRP 0521839696agg.xml CY416B/Elster 0 521 83969 6 June 16, 2004 17:35 4 The Universe of Transitional Justice preferring the forward-looking goal of social reconciliation over the backward-looking goal of retribution. ii. athenian democracy To understand the two transitions and the decisions taken in their af- termath, we have to go back to the beginning of Athenian democracy almost two hundred years earlier. In 594, Solon was given carte blanche by two opposing factions to reform the laws.2 Three of his reforms are directly relevant for transitional justice. He enacted an amnesty law that restored civil rights to those who had been disenfranchised, except ex- iles condemned on charges of homicide or massacre, or for seeking to establish a tyranny.3 This law was the model for the amnesty legislation of 405 b.c. that, in the wake of the defeat of Athens by the Spartan fleet, canceled some of the harsh sentences passed after the overthrow of the oligarchs in 411.4 (The purpose of the amnesty was to reunite the city, but it came too late.) Also, Solon enacted a “peculiar and surprising law, which ordains that he shall be disfranchised who, in time of faction, takes neither side,” the citizen being expected to “espouse promptly the better and more righteous cause, share its perils and give it his aid, instead of waiting in safety to see which cause prevails.”5 Finally, he introduced an important change in the Athenian legal system. Then and later, there was no public prosecutor. All suits had to be brought by private individuals. Solon’s reform was to allow any citizen to start a prosecution, either on behalf of the injured person or simply in the public interest. One effect of the law was to create an incentive for frivolous suits by “sycophants,” or professional denunciators, who would bring a suit against a wealthy man in order to blackmail him by offering to drop the case. They were widely resented by the upper classes, and vigorously prosecuted under the second oligarchy. Other pieces of Solon’s legislation are indirectly relevant, qua impe- tus to a process of democratization that eventually led to untrammeled popular rule triggering an oligarchic backlash. He abolished debt slavery, thereby creating an important condition for effective democracy. Before 2 The basic sources are Plutarch’s Life of Solon and Aristotle’s Constitution of Athens. The latter is usefully interpreted and corrected by Moore (1975). 3 Plutarch, Solon xix.3–4. 4 Andocides, “On the Mysteries,” 73–79. 5 Plutarch, Solon xx.1. P1: KIC/IRP 0521839696agg.xml CY416B/Elster 0 521 83969 6 June 16, 2004 17:35 Athens in 411 and 403 b.c. 5 he enacted his reforms, all citizens could vote in the assembly and serve on the popular courts, but eligibility for some offices was reserved for the nobles (“wellborn”). After the reforms, all criteria of eligibility were defined in purely economic terms, so that birth no longer was decisive. Among the four property classes, members of the lowest were excluded from all state offices. For the most important offices, only members of the top class or the two top classes could be chosen. In 457, members of the third-ranked class became eligible for some of these high offices. Yet even though members of the lowest class remained ineligible, they exer- cised great influence as members of the Assembly, of the popular courts, and (after the reforms of Cleisthenes in 507) of the Council of the Five Hundred, which controlled the agenda of the Assembly. The rights to vote and to hold office may be spurious if their exercise is costly. As Aristotle notes in the Politics (1308b–1309a), “If office bought no profit, then and only then could democracy and aristocracy be combined; for both notables and people might have their wishes gratified. All would be able to hold office, which is the aim of democracy, and the notables would be magistrates, which is the aim of aristocracy.” A decisive step to a more effective democracy was taken by Pericles in the mid–fifth century, when he instituted daily pay for jurors, for members of the Council of the Five Hundred, and for magistrates.6 The class structure could also influence politics by its link to military functions. By and large, the navy was manned by the lowest property class (thetes) and the infantry (hoplites) by the second lowest. As Athens in the period that concerns us was more or less constantly at war, the presence or absence of these groups in the Assembly could sway the outcome: Radical democracy was introduced by Ephialtes’ reforms in 462 which were passed by the Assembly when 4000 hoplites of the middle class were away fight- ing in Messina. Fifty-one years later the radical democracy was replaced by the oligarchic rule of the Four Hundred, and that constitutional change was passed by an Assembly in which the thetes were probably under-represented, because the meeting was held outside the walls and because the entire Athenian navy was stationed off Samos.7 6 Payment for going to the Assembly was established only in the following century. By contrast, at that later time payment for magistrates seems to have been abolished, arguably “a retreat from radical-democratic principles and another sign that the Athenians from 403/2 had opted for a more ‘moderate’ form of democracy” (Hansen 1991, p. 241). Other aspects of this retreat from radical democracy are discussed in Section IV. 7 Ibid., p. 126. P1: KIC/IRP 0521839696agg.xml CY416B/Elster 0 521 83969 6 June 16, 2004 17:35 6 The Universe of Transitional Justice Not surprisingly, the impetus for the restoration of democracy came from that very same navy at Samos. The second-highest group, the cavalry (hippeis), was seen as closely associated with both oligarchies. As members of the Assembly, the Athenians could vote laws and de- crees, but it remained to implement them. Perhaps the most remarkable feature of the full-fledged Athenian democracy is the degree of control the citizens exercised over those who were to carry out their decisions. Al- though most officeholders were chosen by lot, the important offices were elective. Whether chosen by lot or elected, all magistrates had to undergo a mandatory scrutiny before and after taking office. Whereas the ex ante scrutiny was usually a formality (but see Section V for exceptions), the ex post examination could be a serious business. Moreover, magistrates were also subject to prosecution for “crimes against the state.” These control functions had originally been lodged in the Areopagus, an elite body consisting of former high officials belonging to the highest property group, but after the reforms of Ephialtes, they devolved on the Council and finally on the popular courts. By the mid–fifth century, a succession of reforms had created the poten- tial for abuses of unrestrained popular power.8 As reflected in the title of Martin Ostwald’s work, the Athenians had popular sovereignty but not yet the rule of law. For a while, as he also writes, “Pericles’ intelligence and psychological and political insight prevented unreason from dominat- ing policy.”9 One cannot, however, judge the robustness of institutions by looking at the outcomes they generate under good leadership: Enlightened statesmen will not always be at the helm. The next generation of lead- ers, of lesser stature or lesser prudence, showed the vulnerability of the 8 We may wonder how this came about. There was certainly no democratic revolution. Although the masses may have used their voting rights to expand their power, this does not seem to have been the main mechanism. Rather, the elites found it in their interest to sponsor popular measures. Ober (1989), p. 85, notes that “by the time of Cleisthenes, the elites recognized mass ambitions as a new weapon to use against each other. As a result, politically ambitious elites actively sponsored democratizing reforms. . . . Ironically, as the elites gained victories over their enemies by sponsoring democratic reforms, there were fewer and fewer institutions that they could control directly.” Similarly, Ostwald (1986), pp. 179–80, writes that “Ephialtes’ reforms had the effect of establishing the sovereignty of the people in political affairs, but that does not mean this was their intent. His primary purpose may well have been to outflank those who had been most effective in supporting Cimon’s now-discredited policy of ‘giving a higher priority to the interests of Sparta than to the expansion of his own country.’” Ober’s comment is especially interesting, in that it suggests that the elites were engaged in something like a prisoner’s dilemma, in which they all lost power by trying to outdo one another in appealing to the people. 9 Ibid., p. 200. P1: KIC/IRP 0521839696agg.xml CY416B/Elster 0 521 83969 6 June 16, 2004 17:35 Athens in 411 and 403 b.c. 7 institutions. Although the system contained some safeguards,10 these were least effective in the supremely important realm of military decisions. iii. the first oligarchy and its demise Athens had strong expansionist and imperialist traditions. At its height around 460, the Athens-led Delian League comprised nearly two hundred member states in the Eastern Mediterranean. The idea of empire appealed both to the Athenians’ desire for glory and to their desire for tribute. Yet when decisions to go to war were taken by the popular assembly, they were not always wise. In particular, the disastrous Sicilian expedition of 415 was undertaken on a wave of popular enthusiasm, against the more realistic assessment of Nicias. Summarizing Thucydides, Ostwald writes that Nicias himself recognizes that the sobriety and circumspection of his seasoned military expertise have little chance of stemming the irrational enthusiasm of the Assembly (6.9.3). Even before Alcibiades had opened his mouth, lust for adven- ture had made the commons deaf to Nicias’ warnings: a Sicilian expedition would only swell the number of already existing enemies (6.10); even if the expedition succeeded, it would be difficult to control a large population from a great dis- tance, and if it failed in any way, the Sicilians would join the Spartans, eager to recoup their lost prestige, in attacking Athens itself (6.11), and what strength had been recovered after the recent plague should not be dissipated on alien ventures (6.12).11 The effect of the disaster was “the rise of oligarchic opposition, putting all the blame on the leaders who had persuaded the people and on the people themselves for being cozened by them.”12 In the summer of 411, the oligarchs staged a coup and terrorized the assembly into abdicat- ing its powers to them. Organized as the Council of the Four Hundred, they stayed in power for four months only, as the alliance with Persia on which they had counted fell through and the naval troops at Samos turned against them. The restoration of democracy, including transitional justice, took place in two steps. The first (or “intermediate”) successor regime, which lasted 10 These safeguards included notably the use of delegation of decision making to smaller bodies and delays (Ostwald 1986, pp. 78–79; Hansen 1991, p. 307). See, however, Ruzé (1997, Chap. 22) for important reservations to the idea that the role of the Council in preparing proposals for the Assembly served as a delaying device. 11 Ostwald (1986), p. 318. 12 Hansen (1991), p. 40. P1: KIC/IRP 0521839696agg.xml CY416B/Elster 0 521 83969 6 June 16, 2004 17:35 8 The Universe of Transitional Justice for about eight months, was a truncated democracy, limiting franchise to the Five Thousand, “of which body all who furnished a suit of armor were to be members.”13 The regime immediately engaged in what Ostwald calls “a relentless prosecution of extremist oligarchs.”14 Three of them were tried and two executed for treason, because they went on an embassy to Sparta after news of the revolt of the troops at Samos had reached Athens. Some avoided trial by going into exile, only to return in 403 to become members of the Thirty Tyrants. After the restoration of the full democracy, “vindictive measures against those who had been associated with the Four Hundred widened in scope.”15 Soldiers who had stayed in the city during the regime of the Four Hundred suffered partial loss of their political rights.16 Three democrats are cited as having exploited the retributive apparatus for private gain.17 An oligarch who had already been tried and convicted under the intermediary regime was retried under a more serious charge. Yet three indicators show that the measures were not simply victors’ justice. First, as Ostwald adds, “it was a prosecution not a persecution: we hear of no lynchings or terrorism but only of orderly legal pro- ceedings initiated soon after the new regime had been established.” Sec- ond, many who served on the Council of the Four Hundred to the very end were tried and acquitted. Third, the restored democracy resisted the temptation of retroactive legislation. Because there was no law against attempts to overthrow the democracy, the three oligarchs had to be prosecuted for treason; others presumably were not prosecuted at all. Although the new regime enacted a law against such attempts, the legisla- tion was prospective, not retroactive. It was intended to deter “oligarchic recidivism,” not to punish members of the oligarchy that had just been overthrown.18 13 Thucydides, The Peloponnesian War, 8.97.1. This measure, and the abolition of pay for public office, were voted by the people as a whole. 14 Ostwald (1986), p. 401. 15 Ibid., p. 420. 16 Andocides, “On the Mysteries,” 75–76. 17 Lysias, “Defence against a charge of subverting the democracy,” 26. 18 Ostwald (1986), p. 418. In his account of why the “intermediary regime” tried three oligarchs for treason but not for their “revolutionary activities,” Ostwald (1986), p. 402, cites the fact that “their accusers had themselves been active in establishing the Four Hundred and had been members of the Council but had turned against the extremists and were now leaders of the new regime.” After the restoration of the full democracy, this self-serving reason was presumably less important in the explanation of democratic self-restraint. P1: KIC/IRP 0521839696agg.xml CY416B/Elster 0 521 83969 6 June 16, 2004 17:35 Athens in 411 and 403 b.c. 9 iv. the second oligarchy and its demise The next oligarchic regime owes its origin to an event that both discredited the democracy internally and made it vulnerable to external threats. After a great victory in a sea battle against the Spartan fleet off the Arginusae Islands in 406, the Athenians tried eight of their generals for failure to rescue the surviving sailors (or perhaps for a failure to recover the bod- ies of the dead). The proceedings, which may have involved breaches of legality,19 led to the condemnation of all the generals and the immediate execution of the six who were present in Athens. The charged emotional atmosphere that made this outcome possible is captured in Xenophon’s description of what happened when a member of the Council, Callixenus, proposed to vote over the guilt of the generals without a proper trial: Euryptolemus . . . and some others served a summons upon Callixenus, alleging that he had made an unconstitutional proposal. And some of the people applauded this act, but the greater number cried out that it was monstrous if the people were to be prevented from doing whatever they wished. Indeed, when Lyciscus thereupon moved that these men should also be judged by the very same vote as the generals, unless they withdrew the summons, the mob broke out again with shouts of approval, and they were compelled to withdraw the summonses. Furthermore, when some of the Prytanes [the executive committee of the Council] refused to put the question to the vote in violation of the law, Callixenus again mounted the platform and urged the same charge against them; and the crowd cried out to summon to court those who refused. Then the Prytanes, stricken with fear, agreed to put the question – all of them, except Socrates, [who] said that in no case would he act except in accordance with the law.20 The phrase that I have italicized is commonly taken as the most ex- treme expression of unconstrained popular sovereignty in Athens. There is a special irony in that one of the executed generals, Thrasyllus, had been a key actor in restoring the democracy in 411. Although later “the Athenians regretted their action and voted that charges be brought against those who had deceived the people, Callixenus among them,”21 this could not undo the twofold harm that had been done. First, the episode rekin- dled divisions among the citizens and strengthened those who distrusted the democrats. Second, in choosing new generals to replace those who had been executed, the Athenians favored loyalty to the democracy over military competence. In itself, this would not have mattered had the 19 For opposing views on this important point, see Ostwald (1986), pp. 439–41, and MacDowell (1978), pp. 178–79. 20 Xenophon, Hellenica, I.vii. 21 Ibid. P1: KIC/IRP 0521839696agg.xml CY416B/Elster 0 521 83969 6 June 16, 2004 17:35 10 The Universe of Transitional Justice Athenians accepted a peace offer from Sparta after the defeat at Argi- nusae. According to Aristotle, the Assembly rejected the offer because it was deceived by Cleophon, whom he depicts as a notorious demagogue.22 Whether the Assembly acted emotionally or took a calculated gamble based on distrust of Sparta,23 the outcome was disastrous. Led by less- than-outstanding generals, the Athenians suffered a devastating defeat in the battle of Aegospotami in 405, which marked the end of the Athenian empire. In the wake of the defeat, a second oligarchy was installed in 404 under Spartan auspices. The reasons why the Spartans preferred to install a relatively autonomous oligarchic “Vichy” regime, rather than a puppet “Quisling” government, remain conjectural.24 The peace treaty included provisions for the return of the oligarchs who had gone into exile after the collapse of the previous oligarchy, and a vague clause allowing Athens to retain its “ancestral constitution,” a phrase susceptible of several interpretations. In practice, the regime installed by the Thirty Tyrants, as the new oligarchic leaders came to be called, was one of terror. Among other things, they required each of their members to prove his mettle by killing one metic (alien resident). Also, more than fifteen hundred citizens were killed. One motive for the atrocities may have been revenge: The leading oligarch Critias “showed himself eager to put many to death because . . . he had been banished by the democracy”25 after the demise of the previous oligarchy. For some oligarchs, the ultimate goal may have been to remake Athens on the austere model of Sparta.26 Economic gain may also have been a motive. To consolidate their rule, the Thirty created a privileged body of Three Thousand, as they came to be called, and expelled the rest of the citizens from the city. The expelled took up residence in Piraeus, the main port of Athens. Ultimately, with the assistance of an exile democratic army, they routed the oligarchs in battle and killed two of their main leaders. The Spartan leaders once more pulled their punches and supervised a treaty of reconciliation between “the men in the city” and “the men in Piraeus.” According to Aristotle, the terms of the reconciliation were as follows: Those of the Athenians who had remained in the city and wished to leave should live in Eleusis, where they should retain full citizen rights, have complete 22 The Constitution of Athens xxxv.1; see also xxviii.3. 23 For the latter view, see Kagan (1987), pp. 378–79. 24 Ibid., pp. 405–10. 25 Xenophon, Hellenica, II.iii. 26 Ostwald (1986), pp. 485–87. P1: KIC/IRP 0521839696agg.xml CY416B/Elster 0 521 83969 6 June 16, 2004 17:35 Athens in 411 and 403 b.c. 11 self-government and enjoy their incomes. The temple was to be common to both sides. . . . Those living at Eleusis were not allowed to visit the city of Athens, nor were those living in Athens allowed to visit Eleusis, with the exception for both sides at the celebration of the Mysteries. The people at Eleusis were to contribute to a defence fund from their revenues like the other Athenians. If any of those leaving the city took over a house at Eleusis, they were to do it with the agreement of the owner; if agreement proved impossible, each was to select three assessors, and the owner was to accept the price they fixed. Any inhabitants of Eleusis ac- ceptable to the new settlers were to live with them there. Those wishing to move out to Eleusis had to register within ten days of the swearing of the reconcilia- tion oaths if they were in the city at the time, and move out within twenty; those abroad had the same periods from the moments when they returned to Athens. Nobody living at Eleusis could hold any office in the city of Athens until he had been registered as having moved his residence back to the city. Homicide trials in cases where someone had killed or wounded a person with his own hands were to be conducted in accordance with traditional practice. There was to be a total amnesty covering everyone except the Thirty, the Ten, the Eleven and the gover- nors of the Piraeus; even they were to be immune from prosecution once they had rendered their accounts. . . . Those who had held office in the city were to appear before citizens with taxable property. On this basis those who wished to leave could leave the city. Each side was to repay separately the money which it had borrowed for the war.27 The terms of the agreement need some comments. Both sides had to swear an oath to the effect that they would “harbor no grievance” against anyone except for one specific act and four specific groups. Pros- ecution for murder was possible when the accused had killed “with his own hands” (autocheiria). “The means which the Thirty had employed to eliminate their opposition made it difficult, however, for potential plain- tiffs to demonstrate autocheiria in its strictest sense. Few victims of the oligarchy were murdered outright; more often they were deposed by an informer on a spurious charge, arrested, convicted before the oligarchic Council (unless a trial were dispensed with altogether) and compelled to drink hemlock.”28 The four groups excluded from the amnesty were the Thirty Tyrants, the Ten who succeeded them in a brief transitional stage before the restoration of democracy, the Eleven who were responsible for executing the orders of the Thirty, and the governors of Piraeus who administered the port on behalf of the oligarchy. The reference to “render- ing accounts” is to the ex post scrutiny to which all officials were subject. 27 The Constitution of Athens xxxix. 28 Loening (1987), p. 83. The example of Polemarchos discussed in Section V indicates that the demand for each member of the Thirty to kill one metic did not imply that they had to do it by their own hands. P1: KIC/IRP 0521839696agg.xml CY416B/Elster 0 521 83969 6 June 16, 2004 17:35 12 The Universe of Transitional Justice Normally, the scrutiny was carried out by a popular jury chosen by lot among all citizens or even by the assembly as a whole. In this exceptional case, the requirement of scrutiny by citizens with taxable property en- sured that nobody from the lowest property group (thetes) would sit in judgment of the oligarchs, so that former members of the Three Thousand would be overrepresented on the juries.29 It is relevant to mention here that the normal ex post scrutiny was widely seen as a manifestation of untrammeled democracy, capable of leading to “excesses, injustice and plain inefficiency,”30 as when generals were punished for defeats that might be due simply to bad luck.31 Hence, stacking the juries in favor of the oligarchs may have been proposed or accepted by the democrats to signal their intention to retreat from extreme forms of popular rule. The clause may of course also have been proposed or imposed by the Spartans to protect their former allies.32 Other evidence that I shall cite shortly suggests, however, that the returning democrats were willing to limit retribution for the sake of civil peace. Although Aristotle does not mention the fate of property confiscated by the oligarchs, other texts show that this issue was also covered by the treaty. In the summary of Thomas Loening: Individuals who had purchased confiscated goods will retain possession of them, and any property which had not been auctioned off will revert to the original owner. . . . This provision only involves movable property. Presumably, the origi- nal owner would have to establish undisputed title to these unsold goods before regaining possession of them. Acceptance of the reconciliation agreement meant a renunciation of all legal claims to movables confiscated and sold by the oligarchy. There may have been a provision whereby the exiles could repurchase their goods for the amount of money paid by the buyer, provided that he were willing to sell. Such a clause would prevent profiteering on the part of persons who had bought confiscated property cheaply and who then later attempted to sell it back to the original owner at an inflated price. There would be no obligation to resell, unless the buyer wanted to do so. . . . Not all confiscated property remained in the hands of the purchasers. The reconciliation treaty ordains that immovable property, such as land and houses, will be returned to their former owners . . . on the condition that they paid.33 29 Ostwald (1986), p. 499. 30 Ibid., p. 78. 31 See, for instance, Kagan (1981), pp. 318–20. 32 I disagree, therefore, with Loening (1987), p. 49, when he argues for a different reading of Aristotle’s text, on the grounds that “[i]n all likelihood the exiles would not concede such an important advantage which would probably result in the exoneration of many of the oligarchs.” 33 Loening (1987), pp. 51–52. The last clause (“on the condition that they paid”) is conjectural. P1: KIC/IRP 0521839696agg.xml CY416B/Elster 0 521 83969 6 June 16, 2004 17:35 Athens in 411 and 403 b.c. 13 The most significant provision is the distinction between the confiscated goods that had been sold to private citizens and those that remained in the hands of the state. With regard to the former, which might legitimately be claimed by both the old and the new owners, the treaty settled in favor of the new owners. While the new owners were not necessarily oligarchs, they had certainly profited from the oligarchy, yet their gains were not canceled. Here, too, we can see evidence of a willingness to compromise on the part of the returning democrats. The main architects in restoring the democracy were Thrasybulus and Archinos. Thrasybulus, who had led the democrats in exile, was concerned with rewarding those who had struggled on their side. Consequently, he proposed “to give citizenship to all who had had a part in the return from Piraeus although some were manifestly slaves.”34 Archinos was worried, however, that this might change the balance of power in the city too much in favor of the democrats. When the proposal was passed by the Assembly, he had it annulled through a graphe paranomon, a device by which the Athenians could reconsider their own past decisions. Aristo- tle, who praises this move by Archinos, also cites approvingly two other actions, both of questionable legality, that he undertook to cement the reconciliation. First, he arbitrarily abridged the deadline for registration for emigration to Eleusis, thus compelling oligarchs to stay in the city “against their will.”35 Aristotle refers to this as a “sound move,” perhaps because he thought the balance of forces would be as upset by oligarchs leaving the city as it would be by giving voting rights to returning slaves.36 Second, [w]hen one of the returned exiles began to violate the amnesty, Archinus haled him to the Council and persuaded them to execute him without a trial, telling them now they would have to show whether they wished to preserve the democracy and abide by the oaths they had taken; for if they let this man escape they would encourage others to imitate him, while if they executed him they would make an example for all to learn by. And this was exactly what happened; for after this man was put to death no one ever again broke the amnesty.37 An editor of the text comments that Archinos’s “action in attacking someone for violating the amnesty was indeed right, for the only way of 34 Aristotle, The Constitution of Athens xxxx.2. 35 Ibid., xxxx.1. 36 After a few years, however, “the atmosphere in Athens had changed sufficiently to enable Thrasybulus to try again, this time with more discrimination and success, to fulfill his promise to those who had fought on his side” (Ostwald 1986, p. 509). 37 Aristotle, The Constitution of Athens xxxx.2. P1: KIC/IRP 0521839696agg.xml CY416B/Elster 0 521 83969 6 June 16, 2004 17:35 14 The Universe of Transitional Justice reestablishing the state after such a traumatic period was for the Athenians to turn their backs on the past, but it is legitimate to ask whether an illegal execution was the best way of reestablishing the rule of law.”38 In turning their backs on the past, the Athenians resorted to the methods of the past – but they only had to do it once. Although the amnesty did not altogether eliminate lawsuits related to behavior during the oligarchy,39 these were isolated events. A final restraining measure initiated by Archinos, not mentioned by Aristotle, was the enactment of the procedure of paragraphe, perhaps best translated as “counteraccusation.” It is described in a passage from Isocrates that is worth citing at some length: Now after your return to the city from Piraeus, you saw that some of the citizens were bent upon bringing malicious prosecutions and were attempting to violate the Amnesty; so, wishing to restrain these persons and to show to others that you had not made these agreements under compulsion, but because you thought them of advantage to the city, you enacted a law, on the motion of Archinos, to the effect that, if any person should commence a lawsuit in violation of the oaths, the defendant should have the power to bring a paragraphe; the magistrates should first submit this question to the tribunal, and that the defendant who had entered the plea should speak first; and further, that the loser should pay a penalty of one-sixth of the sum at stake. The purpose of the penalty was this – that persons who had the effrontery to rake up old grudges should not only be convicted of perjury but also, not awaiting the vengeance of the gods, should suffer immediate punishment.40 The new procedure thus had a double purpose. The immediate aim was to deter attempts to bring suit in violation of the amnesty. The broader end was to show that the reconciliation agreement treaty had not been imposed by the oligarchs or their Spartan allies, but freely chosen by the democrats in order to promote the good of the city. The moderation displayed by the victorious democrats was quite re- markable.41 In Thucydides, for instance, we find numerous accounts of the horrors of civil war that might have led us to expect a far worse outcome. 38 Moore (1975), p. 272. 39 Loening (1987), Chap. III, has a full account of the cases that arose. 40 Isocrates, Against Kallimachos 2–3. 41 In his catalogue raisonné of violent episodes in classical Greece, Bernard (1999) does not note the lack of vindictiveness following the demise of the oligarchy in 403. The contrast he draws (pp. 423–24) between the vindictiveness of pre-Christian societies and the charitableness of Christianity leaves no room for simple prudence. One can abstain from revenge merely because one perceives that it will be counterproductive, which arguably is what the Athenians did in 403. P1: KIC/IRP 0521839696agg.xml CY416B/Elster 0 521 83969 6 June 16, 2004 17:35 Athens in 411 and 403 b.c. 15 The willingness to show clemency went hand in hand with constitutional reform intended to remove the root causes of oligarchic discontent. A key provision stated that “[t]he magistrates shall under no circumstances whatever employ a law that is not part of the written code. No decree of either Council or Assembly shall have higher authority than a law. No law shall be directed against an individual without applying to all citizens alike, unless an Assembly of six thousand so resolve by secret bal- lot.”42 Also, legislation was removed from the Assembly and delegated to a smaller group of nomothetai. In Ostwald’s words, “The procedures are democratic, since they mandate repeated discussions in the Assem- bly before a new law can be validated, but they represent a restriction on popular sovereignty because the validation does not come from the Assembly but from a broadly based group of nomothetai.”43 Even that smaller group was subject to constraints. If the Assembly, in its annual review of all legislation, found that a set of laws was unsatisfactory, it had to elect five men to speak in the defense of those laws before the matter could go forward to the nomothetai. These long-term measures, which impose procedural constraints on popular rule,44 complement the short- term measures that were taken to alleviate the enmity between oligarchs and democrats. The reconciliation treaty brought about amnesty, but neither oblivion nor silence. Although there are examples of “gag rules” that take certain matters off the table to protect social peace,45 the amnesty decree of 403 is not among them. The clause stating that the Athenians should abstain from harboring grievances did not, as is sometimes asserted,46 impose a total ban on referring to past strifes. It provided immunity for prosecution but did not exclude that a person’s behavior under the oligarchy could be relevant for his suitability to hold public office. Membership of the Council in this period seems to have been viewed as more aggravating than simply belonging to the Three Thousand, although less serious than being one of the Thirty. Nor was the amnesty violated by the decrease in pay for the cavalry, who had largely supported the oligarchy, or by an increase 42 Andocides, “On the Mysteries,” 87. 43 Ostwald (1986), p. 522. 44 MacDowell (1975), p. 74, states that “after the turmoil of 403 the Athenians . . . wanted to make it difficult for themselves to introduce changes in the laws.” Ostwald (1986) similarly writes that the reforms “show that law was to be supreme in the new democracy and that the demos could no longer regard whatever it pleased as valid and binding.” 45 Holmes (1989). 46 E.g., by Loraux (1997). P1: KIC/IRP 0521839696agg.xml CY416B/Elster 0 521 83969 6 June 16, 2004 17:35 16 The Universe of Transitional Justice in pay for the mounted archers, who were more likely to have opposed it.47 The cavalry could also be punished by other means. When asked to send troops to Persia, “the Athenians sent some of those who had served as cavalrymen in the time of the Thirty, thinking it would be a gain to the democracy if they should live in foreign lands and perish there.”48 v. lysias To explore some of these issues, and to view other aspects of the amnesty through the eyes of a contemporary, I shall consider some speeches of Lysias (ca. 458–380). As a resident alien in Athens, he belonged to a group targeted for persecution by the Thirty Tyrants. His brother Polemarchos was put to death by the tyrants, and Lysias himself had a narrow escape. In three speeches delivered between 403 and 399, Lysias discusses moral issues concerning the oligarchs, their supporters, the resisters, and the beneficiaries of their rule, as well as those who chose to remain neutral. In one speech, he personally accuses one of those responsible for the murder of his brother. In another, he writes as a hired pen for a citizen defending himself against the accusation that his passive behavior during the oligarchy makes him ineligible for public office. In the third, Lysias is himself penning such accusations. The speech “Against Eratosthenes,” one of the Thirty, was probably given at the scrutiny of the latter after the fall of the oligarchy. As noted earlier, the jury is likely to have been stacked in his favor, whence certain constraints on the rhetorical strategies Lysias can deploy. Lysias begins by stating that the Thirty moved against resident aliens, alleging that they were hostile to the administration: Therefore they had an excellent pretext for appearing to punish while in reality making money; in any case, the State was impoverished and the government needed funds. They had no difficulty in persuading their hearers, for those men thought nothing of putting people to death, but a great deal of getting money. So they resolved to seize ten, of whom two should be poor men, that they might face the rest with the excuse that the thing had not been done for the sake of money (6–7).49 47 Loening (1987), p. 119; Ostwald (1986), p. 506. 48 Xenophon, Hellenica, III.1.4. 49 The passage raises an intriguing question: Exactly whom were the Thirty trying to fool? In including two poor individuals, the Thirty showed that they were subject to what I have called the “imperfection constraint” in the process of misrepresenting one’s preferences (Elster 1999, pp. 375–80). If the stated aim of an action (persecuting resident aliens for their political views) coincides too well with the agent’s self-interest (confiscating their P1: KIC/IRP 0521839696agg.xml CY416B/Elster 0 521 83969 6 June 16, 2004 17:35 Athens in 411 and 403 b.c. 17 Lysias then states that Eratosthenes had arrested Polemarchos in the street and taken him to prison, where he received the order to drink hemlock: “[M]y brother, as I said before, was put to death by Eratos- thenes, who was neither suffering under any private wrong himself, nor found him offending against the State, but eagerly sought to gratify his own lawless passions” (23–24).50 Against a possible defense by Eratos- thenes that he was acting out of fear and just following orders (25), Lysias responds by asking “whom, in fact, will you ever punish, if the Thirty are to be allowed to state that they merely carried out the orders of the Thirty?” (29–30). Toward the end of his speech, Lysias joins together the “men of the city” and the “men of the Piraeus” as victims (92), saying that he wants to recall the events of that period so that both groups will remember their grievances against the Thirty and their common desire for revenge. He says to the men of the city, “You were so oppressed by the rule of these men that you were compelled to wage war against your brothers, your sons, and your fellow citizens” (92). The purpose of the argument is clearly to make the men of the city, who were overrepresented in the jury, think of themselves as co-victims with the exiled democrats, rather than as co-perpetrators with the Thirty.51 Whereas it would be absurd for Eratosthenes, a member of the Thirty, to claim to have acted under coercion by the Thirty, that excuse is available to their supporters. Yet with the end of the oligarchy, the excuse is no longer valid: “[I]f you condemn this man, you will declare your indignation at the things that have been done; but if you acquit him, you will be recognized as aspirants to the same conduct as [the Thirty], since today nobody is compelling you to vote against your judgment” (90–91). wealth), the claim of being politically motivated lacks credibility. To create an appearance of political motivation, the Thirty would either have to abstain from prosecuting some wealthy individuals or to prosecute some poor ones; the latter strategy is the one Lysias mentions. Yet at the time when the Thirty published a list with the names of the Three Thousand, they decreed “that none of the Three Thousand could be put to death without a verdict of the Council but that the Thirty had the right to put to death anyone not on that list” (Ostwald 1986, p. 486). Since that decree was probably given before the measures against the resident aliens (ibid., p. 487), it is hard to see whom they needed to “persuade.” 50 Note that Lysias here suggests an alternative way in which Eratosthenes could have sought to misrepresent his motives, by claiming to act for personal revenge rather than for gain. In Elster (1999), p. 213, I argue that for the Athenians, acting for revenge, although an inferior motivation to acting for the good of the state, was superior to that of acting out of self-interest. 51 D. Cohen (2001) emphasizes this aspect of much of the post-403 rhetoric. work_gppcjjxbqjeodigel56nm6h75e ---- Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2592876 1 Ethics, Law and Social Justice Kiyoung Kim Professor of Law and Governance The Research Institute Chosun University Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2592876 2 I. Ethics and Responsibility Introduction Ethics and responsibility would be a vexing or awesome topic that the contemporary citizen more likely wishes to avoid to giving his or her views or opinions. That is perhaps because the society transforms rapidly and turns to become more diverse from the past decades. These concepts, on the other, comes not in the ancient or middle era classics, but from the near modern context in 18 th England and French (Cooper, T., 2012). In dealing with the nature and relationship between the two concepts, another notion of morality also comes into a comparative context. Morality, if often interchangeably used with the ethics, could be seen in some differences that ethics is a dimension one step removed from action. So we used to preach our dependents or subjects to conform their conduct to the kind of moral demand, “Exert your best to the interest of nations or society,” “Practice a love and humiliation with brothers, sisters and neighbors,” “Never be drunken while driving,” “Do not commit an adultery or do not steal other’s property,” and the likes. Law, then, would be a minimal of morality which prescribes a prohibited conduct and corresponding criminal sanctions proportionally with the gravity of culpability or social harms (2012). Those concepts might share a common element in a great extent, but could be made distinguished in some of subtleties. US Government on Review One organization comes readily into my mind since it is now engaged in serious problems involving the international human rights, morality, war and politics. The US government facing an issue of Syria tragedy and use of fatal chemical weapons is illustrative. The middle east nations have long been a region of world attention with a political instability, terrorism, antipathy and confrontation and occasional carnage of wars. Most recently Saddam Hussein was held a war criminal to be executed from his unlawful invasion of Kuwait, and Bin Laden also perished from the American justice about his terrorism. Kaddafi also was driven to disappear for his dictatorship and undemocratic cruelty, and many others including an Egyptian consequence of turmoil and radical transformation in 2013. Syria has been charted notorious to perpetrate a years of genocide and persecution which, in years through, awakened the global minds of peace and humanity. The organization, US government, is largely considered a quasi-police regime for the international peace and human rights, which constitute two sublime ideals that the current international community upholds. It operates basically within the US constitution and international laws, but the nature of business possesses a high extent of international politics and diplomacy. Notably, they have to legitimate their sanction or war of alleged justice from UN or other ground of international laws. As the US acts in some ultimate supremacy of UN Security Council in this area of controversy, the right to veto entertained by five major permanent member states in the Council is generally determinative although some grey occasions of legitimacy could be raised and disputed by scholars. Domestically, the issue has ambiguities also involving a constitutional authority waging a war between the Congress and President. It most always tends to avoid a judicial review in its substance and merits since the judiciary often abstains on the ground of political question doctrine. Most practically, the organization has to focus on the attitudes or collaboration of key allies, seriousness of problem, and international atmosphere, risks involved, and the post-war consequences. 3 Ethics and Responsibility with the Neighboring Concepts Across the four concepts mentioned above, i.e., ethics, responsibility, morality and law, we can verify instantly that those share a common ingredient, to say, public value or humanity, religious and traditional beliefs, social custom, exposure and common experience, shared passion, standard of reason in the prevailing context of society and some of learned interplay or receipt among the gross base of people or organizational members. If we consider a morality were to be prime to penetrate the whole of four, we may have a basic dichotomy between the deontological and teleological paradigms of moral assertion (2012). The deontological version of morality would possess a more quality of absolutism on a desired human conduct and behavior. That likely defines a context of each individual in the face of God or prevailing custom, and meditates through the flesh and spiritual ideals. The deontological approach, thus, often induces one unavoidable solution and prefers a consummation of ideals without alternatives or options. This less likely allows the circumstances or relativistic nature of moral issues to operate in guiding the conduct of individual or organization. It would, in general sense, only be possible in a limited scope of inalienable values, more likely be pertinent with an individual than organization, more religious than social in apprehension, less likely to compromise and so on. The teleological frame of morality often presupposes a utilitarian concept, hence, more likely relativistic, circumstantial, interactive or communicative, reciprocal, evolutionary, and etc. It pursues a greatest good in the greatest number, and has quality to compromise and improve (2012). Then, this dichotomy, in some sense, could be seen to correspond with two perceptions of J.S. Mill on liberty, to say, hedonic nature of pleasure and higher pleasure. In the context of organization and public administration, the teleological concept of morality contributed profoundly to the ethics of bureaucracy and responsibility of public employees. An exploration of ethics would be in two ways, which are descriptive of the process how the individual or organization applies their ethical concept to their conduct and organizational decision making (2012). The other would be normative so that the leaders or decision makers are compelled or practically demanded to abide by and uphold a certain set of values, job requirement, organizational culture and workplace democracy. Some Thoughts on Their Relationships From the above, we can derive several points of relationship between the ethics and responsibility. First, the ethics are presumed on some of societal or organizational context while the responsibility is affiliated with a role, discipline, or sanction and particularized form of realized ethics (Laureate Education Inc., 2013). Without the concept of role or responsibility, the ethics would be practically small thing to be only instructive and inculcating. The ethics are generated and continue or evolve in interplay with the system, process, culture, intelligence and rationale or reason, which, if in a specific context, would be prevailing and governing if some lesser extent of coercion and compulsion than law. Hence they are more objective and persistent on the given society and organizations, but can conflict among each other if deviated from a specific sphere. For example, the ethics between the interested nations about a Syrian incident would not be same or even conflict about the phenomenon and governing ethics. On other case, we may see a 4 conflict of ethics between the justice department and Mafia organization. Given that a Huntington’s forecast on the clash of culture denotes as a most factor in the contemporary world politics, the conflict of ethics would be more bureaucratic or organizational in connotation and mid-colored between the law and culture. This implies that the ethics could be more specific, more organized and tangible in recognition and apprehension of the concerned, more operationalized in action, convincing, and substantial or comprehensive, which is other than culture, but might be lesser than law. This implies that the ethics would be more readily applied to the concept of responsibility, and offers the basis to pursue a responsibility other than culture (The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Ethics, 2013). Given this attribute, the US government would be more properly conceived in view of ethics and as one of organization rather than the nation or state, which lacks the kind of absolute legitimacy unlike the domestic politics (2013). If we say culture, that would mean a kind of retreat or high of conceptual drawback because of its rigidities and irreconcilable nature at basics. On the other hand, more formalistic approach from the normative nature or international law, that would lack an agility or strategic aspect to secure a peace or human rights. This conception would be practically less wrong if we guess on a more likelihood that President Obama and his national security council would consume much of his time on, inter alia, strategic slides or projections, action or time plan, involved stakeholders than the books describing the cultural differences or historical antipathy as well as than the UN chapter, constitution or statutes. Conclusion: Application of the Concepts Then, the ethics US government has to identify and respect would not be new in a vast context of established sensibilities or understanding. As a quasi-police role state in the world, we could be conventional and less skeptical of what decision US government has to make and act. Perhaps I would not be incorrect to label the US a quasi-police role state if bipolarity or multi-polarity would be respectfully suggested by the scholarly circle of international politics. That would be dissimilar with the late 1990’s and early millennium years, that the ethics or responsibility from a war and the military operation, in its process, could also not be the same. Obviously, the President and his council members would assume a divergent and complicated context of cooperation and collaboration if Russia vetoed a military operation. UK, traditionally a key ally in the international peace keeping operation, denied a ready collaboration unless any sufficient evidence are to be gathered to support the legitimacy of action by further steps of UN. Then the ethical nature of this issue might turn to be more likely a morality dispute which would be less organized and requires a solitude of basic beliefs (Laureate Education, Inc., 2008). This aspect shows a dynamism or more circumstantial nature of ethics than law or morality, which would be organizational or bureaucratic than the state or religion. The responsibility may be viewed in two spheres, i.e., objective and subjective (Cooper, T., 2012). The ethical administrators have a deep awareness of values, beliefs, traditions, norms and standards, and specific context of organizational goals and democratic virtues. They are conforming to the ethics of organization and do not breach it, which flavors in any given or objective context of system and interaction on ethics. When we consider the subjective responsibility on ethics, we often require them to exercise his best wisdom and inner process to reach some specific decision in the belief to uphold the ethics. Hence, responsibility seeks to unravel the specific application of ethics and can be viewed as enhanced and particularized form of ethics to ensure a process reengineering and vitality 5 or morality of organizational performance. Given its political nature of issue, the responsibility of President and his cabinet or council members also largely are political. Hence, unethical decision, which would perhaps be to undermine the set of values or democratic virtues, realistic lesson from the past, general conviction of American people, and amicability of international community, might bring a loss of next election, domestic reaction in an acid criticism and international disrepute of American prestige. References Laureate Education Inc. (2013). Course Preview and Course Introduction :Ethics and Social Justice. Cooper, T. (2012). The Responsible Administrator. San Francisco, CA: John Wiley & Sons. Laureate Education, Inc. (2008). Ethics and social justice. Baltimore: Author. "Philosophical Roots" with Amanda Baker (approximately 11 minutes). The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Ethics. Retrieved Sep. 2, 2013 from http://www.iep.utm.edu/ethics/. The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Responsibility. Retrieved Sep. 2, 2013 from http://www.iep.utm.edu/responsi/. http://www.iep.utm.edu/ethics/ http://www.iep.utm.edu/responsi/ 6 II. Some Thoughts on the Morality and Ethics The Concepts, their Quality and Connection Morality is generally defined as a code of conduct as the guide for an action or conduct, which would be formed, upheld, and testified by any particular society or social groups (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Morality, 2013). In comparison, ethics is often discussed about the ways of desired state for an agent or being where he or it could thrive or rest in pleasure, philia, good character and good will (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Ethics, 2013). Ethics, therefore, may be approached in our usual contact, say, friendship. Ethical conduct or behavior often leads to a friendship in which an individual would consider the factors, say, usefulness, good moral character or pleasure in making a friend. For Aristotle’s, a friend could not be many, but small in number since the true friendship could only be possible by protraction of lived experiences and sharing. Hence, the ethics often can be more friendly engrafted with the discourse of leadership and organization. Morality often is said of a minimal of law, and this description also could be true between the ethics and morality. Hence, morality offers a basic ingredient of ethics that the immoral leaders would never be received as an ethical leader. Ethics, however, generally requires something more in addition to the moral requirements (2013). Morality would repudiate an organicism generally that the reason, religion, tradition and social custom are a principal source to found the elements of morality. Ethics, therefore, concerns a relationship, interactive dimension, and constructive pleasure in sharing and existence. Morality would pursue a human aspect leading to some of inviolable code of conduct, and often be conceived to cover a general base of people within the society. That leads to the difference that morality would be more friendly with the politics and citizenry while the ethics would be more linked with the bureaucracy and various forms of organization. This would bring that the scope of influence would differ. Morality would be seen as more plenary and influence in a larger scope as in the case of Kantian universalism or J.S. Mill’s essence of civilized liberty. However, the conflict, at least a differing perception about the morality, is some of usual phenomenon as we see in the Oriental and Occidental virtues. For example, Good Samaritan law dictates the moral obligation, later developed into the principle of case law, that nobody betrays the nature of order, hence morality in our concern, even if we does not offer a rescue effort for the person in predicament. Once he is involved in the rescue activities, the duty is created to tender any best reasonable way to save him or her from the danger and perils. Oriental morality, as propounded by the Saint as named Mencius, goes otherwise that one is intuitively driven and morally demanded to rescue a drowning child. Other illustrations about a different concept of morality would span widely with the Muslim, Christian, Quakers, homosexuals, Buddhist adherents, and even between the socialists and liberalists (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Morality, 2013). In this purview of subtlety about the unversalization and sectarianization, morality could not be said definitely to enjoy a larger scope of respect than the ethics. A morality often phases in the dimension, which is fundamental and basic, and that possesses the quality to expand and even coerce. The typical contrast as perceived by Roman rulers between the citizens of Rome and barbarians of periphery may presuppose a superiority of their morality, civilization, system and tradition. One historian also comments on the nature of western imperialism as a moral conquest and westerners’ lesson against the Orient or uncultivated barbarianism. Kantian universalism, and his protégé, Hegel’s thesis d’état raison perhaps would work as a prelude 7 for a Hitler’s excessive or abusive expansionism of Germanian sanctity or superiority against the exterior morality. So the morality possesses a character of ultimacy and inviolability, hence, fairly religious, but on reason, custom and tradition which would be a relative factor to intercourse with other group or society of different morality. This relativism would require a tolerance more than the ethics since the moral conviction is fundamental and easily embedded in any irreconcilable beliefs. It also can be made keenly affiliated with the politics on campaign and organization that a dissidence or sectarianism is a matter of course to shape the federal constitutionalism in the American continent in 18 th century. Ethics, on the other, is formed relatively and interactively to reach some of pleasant state. Hence, it entails the quality of human condition and eclectic nature depending on the circumstances. Hence, the word can be dealt with the concept of social justice as seen in the title of this course (Laureate Education Inc., 2013). The concern of social justice or welfare, in the earlier of 20th century, plainly reveals an evolution of circumstances from the orthodoxy in belief between the liberalism and quest for a political dominance in the mid of 19 th century. If the latter assimilates an operation of morality through the basics of capitalist society, the turn of 20 th century to see the social justice would come possible as the kind of ethics from a general base of improved wealth, a market failure and polarization of society, increased representation and extended role of the elected officials, and so on. As Aristotle postulated, the ethics can be facilitated by the paradigm of virtuous agent, which would be mutatis mutandis a proactive nature of character in the contemporary equation. Hence, it is positive and proactive while the morality would largely be defensive and conservative on the tradition or basic disposition of each person or agent. His three companion idols, say, contient, incontinent, and evils, is simple but facile to show the contrast involving the four types of character (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Ethics, 2013). Contient is a knoweldged person, but stern to keep staying with the counter-pressure. Incontientis ignorant, and did not appreciate the nature, condition, necessary things and events. This, of course, leads to any vulnerability and weaknesses in responding to the counter-pressure. Evils are out of merits to obfuscate and confuse the nature of challenges or undermine the existing conditions to harm an agent or organization. The virtuous agents, in comparison, would be a most idealistic quality as a leader or governor, but this does not necessarily means these persons are best lived nor always bring an affirmative consequence to improve and cultivate. For the Aristotle’s case, the good character and good will come into play to construct an understanding of ethics (2013). One other important focus was drawn from the intelligent or knowledge dimension of human condition, what he called philia (2013). So the concept likely represents a modern dualism about an inner human dimension which cover a consciousness or cognizance and intent. As Duke William conquered the Great Britain in 1076, an agent acts on his intent and will, who would perhaps operate their firms or enterprises on good will.As Sir. Coke and Blackstone spelt on the principles of common law, the leaders of organization are some knowledgeable person to guide the followers in any kind of blackletter rules, often implicitly, however, in his dimension of philia. Aristotle viewed a priori existence of political community or polity before an agent or person. This implies that the ethics and virtue of leadership are one of central qualities although he saw a happiest life in philosophers or their ways of living. These ingredients to compound into the whole of ethics simply show a major difference from the morality. To say, the morality is orienteered dominantly toward an inner dimension of humanity, but the ethics often is expressed in the apparent way, and is interchanged interactively and relationally. Morality often pursues a self- perfection, consistency with the 8 code of conduct in fulfilling a satisfaction of self, as well as avoidance of self collapse. That nature would be dominant even if we occasionally encounter an agent or entrepreneurs morally condemned in the newspaper stories or others. We can see that the knowledge or intent comes to serve relationally and enables a beginning point to interact and lead. A theory of appreciative inquiry would show this in a fashion. The leaders or strategy finders begin his job by inquiring, hence knowledge, in the intent, hence will, to encourage their target organizations. Ethics would require a course of journey to create a pleasant condition of humans and organizations while the morality often is given by an exterior authority as a code of conduct. Hence, a friendship illustration in the discourse of ethics is fairly apposite to reveal the context of differences for two thesis (2013). Let me say some more about recent chores. Reflections from My Recent Experience I have experienced some of displeasure in conducting my lecture series. I have borrowed a specially equipped lecture room for videotaping in this fall term. The videotaping failed once in time last week to display without an audio effect. It also failed again to overlap the two lectures into one piece or might be hacked or stolen, which removed, in no way, a half of class from two hours content. The failure involves an incomprehensible technical difficulties about the computer device and attendant facilities that lay professors could not handle. The paid staffs, who often are graduates of college, were available, but they hardly penetrated the core of technical issues. Their advice is meeker, and most profoundly, other principals in charge are very negative about the use of special room. They are fairly defensive and like to be loyal to the original purpose of that room as a matter of school policy. Actually, however, the policy seems flexible and the hard nature of my course has a good justification for videotaping at the aim of post-school studies for the students. This negative stance of college administrators and less will of theirs seem to create an atmosphere to influence the technical staffs. Their skills and knowledge also seem imperfect to perform their role and service. I got infuriated with the two times failure in sequence. I do not even like to speak of any rule consequetialiam or act consequentialism in this case. However, the ethics are only way to explain this displeasure. The school administrators and technical staffs never are immoral and I could not tell any specific point in violation of any code of conduct. They stay peacefully to be satisfied and look likely to keep with a good moral character. The only way to explain my anger would be from their inaction, as likely contientor incontient. They are never immoral, but merely neither virtuous nor proactive against the counter-pressure. They hang around half of hours for one hour class by reserving any definite advice about the use of special mike. They are never immoral, but we can hardly find any friendship, a useful equivalent with ethics in analogy. Ethics, then, would be an enhanced concept for the desired human or organizational condition (2013). Reference Laureate Education Inc. (2013). Ethics and Social Justice "Fundamental Concepts" with Amanda Baker (approximately 16 minutes). 9 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: The Definition of Morality. Retrieved Sep. 7, 2013 from http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/morality-definition/. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Aristotle's Ethics (parts 1-4). Retrieved Sep. 7, 2013 from http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-ethics/. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/morality-definition/ http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-ethics/ 10 III. A Comparative Understanding of Liberalism and Libertarianism The Main Profile of Two Thoughts Liberalism and Libertarianism are close concepts, but distinguished in the basis and its present effect on the community. A libertarianism begins with the self full- ownership and penetrate the kind of property or physics origin of metaphor through the discourse (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Libertarianism, 2013). It provides the ways to understand a personal autonomy, and its relations with the community and governance. Its contemporary evolution would be less extensive and took the nature of countervailing theme against the paradigm of welfare state or egalitarian liberalism. It tends to seek some of strengthened or defensive logic concerning a lesser intervention, more enhanced conception of personal autonomy from the social justice, as well as an emphasis on distinction between the society and polity or government. Hence, the ideas of libertarian adherents may go into an anarchy or requires a stern justification about the intervention, any scheme of administration on justice or new community ideals. Its tradition, in due course, can be traced back to Lockean ideas and its contemporary leading theorist would be Nozick (2013; R. Nozick, 1977). A liberalism would begin to perceive one as an agent more than the libertarianism that it spans widely thorough the human nature and interaction within the polity or political community (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Liberalism, 2013). This ideal generally is considered to play a foundational role in the evolution of western democracy through 18 and 19 th centuries in UK and US. Its origin should get more extended, but its significance as an ideal was framed in the moment as a new social idea in the 16-19 th century western community. It is the kind of rebellious understanding from the prevailing purview of those times from the feudal subjectivity and later a divinity of monarch. One or agent is not autonomous or self-willed to be liberal, and current form of freedom or liberty would only be attributed to the limited scope of people. This perception had broken at first with the struggle between the King, a representation of new nationalism in Europe and Pope, and resolved in the Westphalia peace regime. A next phase would be the contention between the wealthier class and ancien regime as represented by the feudal system and monarchy. In this phase, the contractarian theory offered the ground to liberalize the class of commercial merchants, industrialists, and local agrarians, and other class of bourgeois. It reshaped a dominant version of nobility, divinity and feudal ethics into a new paradigm and ways of understanding. Hobbes, Locke and Rousseau are considered as leading three originators of this ideal, who had, nonetheless, subtle differences in proposing their social contract in theory and basics (2013). From this social contract frame, a limited government could be enabled and the abuse of power may be checked or kept in balance in its structure and function. That means that the people turned to become qualified to enjoy their inalienable rights, such as rights to life and liberty as well as property right. The divinity of monarch was said of illusion to be replaced by a new hypothesis of social contract while Hobbes did not advance to this extent. The ideal of liberalism made a profound impact on the basic structure of democratic rule in the late of 18 th , notably on the constitutionalism in US and universalism of human rights in France. This ideal, philosophically enriched by the work of J.S. Mills, served as a dominant perspective to rule the conquered lands and countries by the British power in the Victorian age. 11 From the idea of J.S. Mills on liberty, we can learn much of human condition, the duty and responsibility of agent, ethics, and ways of interplay to implant or inculcate himself and neighbors (J.S. Mill, 2002). In his conception, therefore, the liberty is not restrictive to the negative concept from coercion or compulsion. Beyond this basic liberty, he evangelized many intrinsic in his philosophical deliberation to substantiate the views of liberty or liberalism to bridge toward the positive concept of liberty. For example, he saw that the context of individual to grow and learn is essential to ensure the liberalism. He also distinguished the doctrine of free trade from the principle of individual liberty, and taught that the justification of personal and economic liberty was distinct (2002). He diversified the true nature of one or agent, and enabled to explicate the unraveled dimension of humanity if just philosophically or as unsupported by the contemporary science on humanity or psychology. Mill's perfectionism and his conception about the two ways of pleasure, hedonic and higher ones has likely echoed in consonance with the modern views on the Maslow’s hierarchy of human needs. He is also available in contrast with the Marxism provided that Marx is purely mercantile and economic in viewing the society on its basics. Millian concept might be received as a false consciousness from the communist adherents in one way, and may bring a structural distaste for the scholars of colonial experience. In his words, we can read, “Despotism is a legitimate form of government in dealing with barbarians, provided the end be their improvement…” (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Liberalism, 2013). This view yet would likely be disfavored by Koreans in the context of Japanese imperial rule or US in the context of British rule. I consider, however, his idea is pioneering to flourish a reasonable pluralism and also interesting as if he whispered the Victorian glory of larger opportunities and ample space to fill the civilization errand in the ruled lands. That comes, for example, by mentioning about developing individuality and cultivating capacities. He therefore saw the barbarians not be qualified to entertain a genuine nature of liberty, but could be improved by ways of contact and interaction, which would likely be a Darwinian understanding of our nature (J.S. Mill, 2002). Then the views from the group of distaste likely said that they become as equal to be civilized but in the limits of British hierarchy and convenience of imperialistic rule. I am not sure if Marx, who might be a close peer as a matter of time with Mill, had that point, but Marxist view may overstate the role and capacity of working class to reject the idea of evolutionism. This hypothetical bridge would not be incorrect if we institutionalized a tripartite convention among the labor, capital and government in Korea and Northern European states. One other attribute in these times would likely be the experimental journey of new democratic rule unlike the Victorian system of world governance. The governments in the new continent around the mid of 19 th century had been aching to settle their system of rule and contested points about the democratic virtue and desires. Notably, the civil war and women’s right to suffrage were lodged to contend and evolved. This means any vulnerabilities and weaknesses in terms of the public policy and administration around the times. As J.A. Hobson phrased, the elected officials now are true representatives of the community in competence, capacity and ethics than a mere defender of their wealth as formerly stigmatized (2013). The concept of social justice and ethics of bureaucrats began to maturate if we are in the D.G Richie’s, “genuinely the government of the people and by the people themselves” (2013). This growth of government against the market or wealthier class rule would perhaps notably break into the New Deals around 1930’s and the social welfare or justice concept tend to come into some of primacy for the public administrators. A subtlety can be raised between the views of John Rawls and the paradigm of welfare state, and that the 12 term, “egalitarian liberalism” may more properly investigate the current context of humanity, social justice and ethics of administrators. While the welfare thesis highly tilted on any economic discourse, the egalitarian liberalism is prone to see the people and their social justice in some depth of philosophical justification as in Mill’s case against the pure market theorists (Laureate Education Inc., 2013). Interestingly, a point developed into the classical idea of Plato and his disciples about the function and role of individual in the community and the kind enabling concept between the deprived nations and affluent ones. A substantive justice or positive liberty would surge in the threshold to practice the liberalism as a matter of polity. For example, Ely asserted a social justice and positive liberty for the working class which replicated the ideas of post- modern constitutionalism about an enabling concept of rights on the labor and social welfare benefits. A Summary on Two Thoughts Then the liberalism may be classified on several of its basics as (i) thoroughgoing methodological individualism (ii) individualistic postulate’ against all forms of ‘organicism’, (iii) expansion of an abstract conception of individual selves as pure choosers and ingratification of ideas on the cultural membership and other non-chosen attachments and commitments (iv) aims at development on a decent hierarchical society (v) horizon to explore the social cooperative structure and justice (2013). Interestingly, Mill adverted on the virtue of non-intervention on the non-liberal states which raises an ambiguities how this proposition could apply to non-British subjects or other powers at his time and contemporaries. For example, a previous illustration about Syria comes to be tested in his thesis. Also we can illustrate other ramifications of liberalism such as public reason liberalism and radical pacifism, which would adaptively propose to respond to the circumstances and demand of environment. For example, Republican liberalism could be epitomized in its new ways about the failure of free market structure globally, and economic in its vast aspect of proposition and arguments. Libertarianism, as above introduced, could be viewed in a protesting thesis against the imprudence of social justice or dominant ethics they consider thematically unproved or over- generalized. Hence, they question the prevailing ideas of contemporary society from a rule consequentialism and teleology or rule cotractarianism. The impression would likely be the context of Scooridge who churns on the legitimacy and justification of social justice or established course of governmental ethics. They may constantly raise a suspicion and demand any plausible ground to legitimate the actions and programs by the justice-promoting organizations. Nonetheless, they have a cause and rationale that the public administrators should not disregard. Two Thoughts and Ethics Ethics, in Aristotelian preaching, was viewed for phasing out of virtuous agent in impression and a paragon to reach the idealistic dimension of mean state (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Aristotle's Ethics, 2013). Aristotle showed a contrast within three other characteristics, say, contient, incontinent, and evil. A good person chooses to act virtuously, and transcends the knowledgeable, yet inactive person without a public outreach 13 for justice. Kalon, a Greek word in English meaning “beautiful,” “noble,” or “fine”, would be an ideal that the kind of person pursues (2013). This character of agents or person perhaps would be a best lived life on knowledge and understanding as coupled with the second mode, a devotion to politics. For the public administrators or students on the course of journey, I suppose that the ideals of liberalism would be a central point to tackle with to contest the virtue of administration every constantly. In this nexus, the ethics can come into an interplay, and libertarianism also would be an approach of neighbors which advises to communicate for and construct the system into a meaning (Laureate Education Inc., 2013) Reference J.S. Mill (2002). The Basic Writings of John Stuart Mill: On Liberty, the Subjection of Women and Utilitarianism. New York, NY: Modern Library. Laureate Education Inc. (2013). Ethics and Social Justice "Fundamental Concepts" with Amanda Baker (approximately 16 minutes). R. Nozick (1977). Anarchy, State, and Utopia.Basic Books. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Aristotle's Ethics (parts 1-4). Retrieved Sep. 7, 2013 from http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-ethics/. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Liberalism. Retrieved Sep. 7, 2013 from http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/morality-definition/. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Libertarianism. Retrieved Sep. 7, 2013 from http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-ethics/. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-ethics/ http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/morality-definition/ http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-ethics/ 14 IV. Ethics and Design Approach Conflict and Ethics The public administrators are responsible to address the issues and agenda, and may, in some cases, need to make a difficult decision ethically viewed as divergent in ways of dealings. Most notably, they may be required to decide or act in the tension concerning the conflict of authority, interest and role. How the two concepts are connected and interact among each other often matters in the circumstances where the issue, task, course of dealings, agenda, and their role performance come to impose a difficult avenue of ethical consideration beyond the routine course of making a decision. There can we identify the class of conflict which corresponds with the three elements, say, authority, personal interest, and work role (Cooper, T., 2012). A conflict of authority occurs when the ethical dilemma relates with the law, line hierarchy of organization or work structure, and other formal or informal work requirements in terms of control, cooperation or collaboration (2012). A conflict of interest often arises that the organizational course of performance, its goals or missions overlap the sphere of personal interest directly or indirectly, obviously or impliedly, as well as in the spectrum on purity and fidelity from the collective frame of organization. It does not necessarily require a loss or harm to the organization, and merely an improper or disloyal connection between the organization and interested administrator can suffice the conflict of interest test. The personal interest may not be the administrator’s himself, but encompasses that of his spouse or close siblings in general. A drafting of ethical code depends on the nature of organization and public policy as seen in the case of New York code on the professional ethics of bar members. In that enactment, the conflict of interest was narrowly tailored to have a limited ambit about the financial aspect when it defines an impermissible scope of violating the conflict of interest requirement. A conflict of role would be found more flexibly, and pertains to some of professional dimension on the desirabilities, efficiency of administrative performance, as well as the organizational or social utility of agents or administrators (2012). The concept is less rigid in comparison with the conflict of authority, but dynamic and creative in pursuit for a better performance, which, however, interplays to comport with the laws and line hierarchy. The concept of role, therefore, substantiates the formal or perfunctory nature of authority, and intrinsically relates with the administrative responsibility. While both of authority and role incur an issue of administrative responsibility, the former more directly brings the problem of objective responsibility. The latter would extend to the dimension of subjective responsibility while the basics of role also interplay with an objective responsibility. Ethical Reflections and Responsibility on the Design Approach The topic, in nature, entails a difficult dimension in the course of professional service as a public administrator, and often reshores into the ethical dilemma or the conundrum of how to find a fit to resolve it (Hicks, D., 2013). According to Cooper, the design approach would serve a convenience and his or her ways to address the job duties about an ethical issue faced during the course of performance (Cooper, T., 2012). The paradigm, then, needs to be incorporated into his or her daily practice to chart and monitor his performance and standard. The use of this ethical model brings a benefit. This would serve finding a legitimacy of his or her authority and role, and particularly useful when he was questioned about his exercise of 15 authority and role. This means that the design approach could be a useful tool to address any predicament from the claim on subject responsibility. He or she also would be smooth with an autonomous performance of learned behavior sequence, and remove an ad hoc trouble on each respective case (2012). In his view, there are two types of ethical decision model, say, descriptive and prescriptive (2012). The descriptive model shows the ethical decision as the world is while the prescriptive one introduces the ethical decision as the world we would like it to be. His ethical decision model is prescriptive and framed into stages and factors. The first would require our perception about the ethical problem posed as a challenge. Then the administrators begin to describe the problems and define the ethical issues in forms to be explored and finally anticipated to resolve. He or she explores a scope of alternatives to be chosen, and will be required to explore a projection of probable consequences and its analysis. In the next, he stepped into the phase of selecting an alternative, a best fit as confirmed through the process. Finally, he or she imagines the picture that would be realized by implementation of his or her decision, say, state of resolution (2012). The model would be an amalgam of device to enable a leverage of ethical analysis into the express design which would be a dynamic process, rational and principled, but also on human feelings and character (Laureate Education, Inc., 2008). The design approach could increase the attitudes of administrators, i.e., reexamination, respect for the principles, distinction between values and principles, and so on. It would also cultivate the public administrators to think in a principled fashion. The ethical dilemma in its most extent brings an agony leading that the ethical autonomy is reduced to zero, that character is eroded, and that integrity is undermined (Cooper, T., 2012). From this hardship, the design approach can shape some of stable process within the inner minds of administrator which facilitates the nature of ethical analysis, i.e., primordal, spontaneous, complex, logical, principled, and relatively comprehensive justification (2012). Ethical Dilemma and Conflict of Authority, Role and Interest Across three concepts, we may find a Korean illustration about the course of military coup in Dec., 12 th , 1979. The incident may be known to US citizens if Korea is one of key allies and its rising prestige as a world class of nation. General Chun, a Korean of mid fifties, had served as a chief of investigatory authority to probe an assassination and cruel killings of presidential aids in the attempt to terminate the Cheng-hee Park’s lengthy reign on a militaristic ground. Jae-kyu Kim, a chief of National Intelligence Service and conspiracy leader of the plot to assassinate, alleged his legitimacy of killings given the democratic ethos and popular quest to restore the democratic rule, as shown in the Bu-ma marches and confrontation charted around 1979. Mr. Kim was actually executed, and was rejected of his claim in the judicial process. General Chun, a chief of Military Intelligence Service, was appointed as a charge of investigation by Seung-wha Chung, General in Chief of Korean Army. General Chun is required to directly report to the command and order from General Chung as a matter of law and line authority. General Chun had been a key actor of informal fraternity group, what was called Hanahoei, which is powerful and potent under the shield of Park’s support. General Chung’s background was different, who is not a graduate of Korean Military Academy, but was educated in a general base of military training. Hanahoei is a firm club in the promise to share a same destiny, personal welfare, promotion opportunities and 16 career success, and of course, a loyalty to the Park’s administration. The two months from Oct. 1979 through December of that year apparently looked of peace and progressive transition toward the aspired democratic form of government. Three Kims, promising candidates for the next presidency enjoyed a public attention, and the nation gradually had maturated into a campaign mood and political flourishing. That appears certain in due course that Koreans would sooner witness a democratic government long aspired and in the moment of demise of militaristic regime. Chun’s role is obvious in the eyes of public to investigate Kim and his conspirators or accomplice, while General Chung would govern temporarily in responding to the national emergency (Laureate Education Inc., 20o8). A transition to the regular regime seemed ensured in 1980. Abruptly, however, an unauthorized fire battle awakened Koreans in Dec. 12 th , 1979, which broke out in the course of arresting activities of General Chung by General Chun. He later obtained an approval of that arrest by the acting head of state, Kyu-ha Choi, but in the demonstration of his informal power with his fraternity members. Some of implicit coercion can be noted in the evolution of one night revolutionary course of action. Chun’s cause and rationale, later seriously questioned and debated in the courtroom and by many political analysts, were alleged to lie in the investigatory needs about a suspicious behavior of General Chung, at the night of assassination. General Chung was called to report by Kim, and attended a dinner in the near guest room of Blue House close to the place of assassination. Chun’s version is that his presence had been necessary to support the coup of Kim and might imply a conspiracy connection with Kim. He, therefore, had no way to attempt an arrest of his direct supervisor without the approval of president, which had been required as a matter of law (20o8). A prior approval might fail the plan to arrest, but may bring a counteraction from the General in Chief. This scenario would be worse and Chun’s claim was that a possible culprit to harm the national head might continue by sacrificing him. In the period, there was an alleged plan to transfer General Chun and his informal fraternity group to some of marginalized position. As said, they had been strongly associated to serve their spirit and prosperity in their military career. This atmosphere to counter the Hanahoeiprobably threatened their personal expectations that they would turn to react in defending their private interest and in the chance to forge their suspicion about a General Chung’s quandary on the said night (20o8). What motives actually would be more imposing is still dubious, but might well be combined to make the decision to arrest. That night a number of innocent lives were sacrificed, and the divisions or special combat unit were mobilized at the military command order appropriated to serve their unauthorized course of military operation in arresting General Chung. At the time of arrest on Dec, 12, 1979, he spent his time off duty in his public house located at Hannam-dong guarded by the armed military police. This guard line was broken by the attack of his appropriated unit, and other forces were drawn to occupy the command center of Korean Army. This story reveals the context of critical dilemma in terms of ethics and code of conduct on the public administrators. General Chun was responsible to investigate, gather the evidence, and transfer his findings to the prosecution authority of Korean Army. His competence and authority was prescribed expressly by the law and work flows in system and practice. He would also need to report to his supervisor, General Chung and eventually to the acting president. He certainly faced an ethical dilemma how to decide and what course of action he should have to undertake. His deliberation perhaps would go into any deeper analysis the administrators normally would not process. The design approach and ethical decision model might seriously work around the perception of ethical problems, defining an ethical issue, exploring the scope of alternatives, and finally a selection of alternative and 17 state of resolution (Cooper., T., 2012). His ambition as a loyal and faithful cardinal of Korean Army, and human feelings from a Park’s benevolence might move him ethically as a factor. A retreat from any radical action would undermine his and his peer’s military career and personal welfare. His personal conviction to restore the justice and unearth the truths of that night might come highly to risk a military confrontation between the same armies, and eventually his and his peers’ lives (Hicks, D., 2013). His status, however, stood in the conflict of authority which transgressed the law and expected course of action (Cooper, T., 2012). A formality of line authority was clearly violated, but the role analysis may, in some degree, come to favor his courage and blatant initiative to arrest. A conscience, loyalty, passion, and affinity may support his decision. One source confirmed that he called President Park as a father in the informal gathering, and both had been ethically tied. In any case, a US Ambassador as well as the commander of the Eighth Division for Korean Ambit at that time, got infuriated about his usurpation of authority. The Korean government also finally condemned his decision and course of actions as a military coup in the criminal jurisprudence. The context of subjective responsibility was, in heat and passion, contended and debated seriously in the courtroom around 1994. An argument to legitimatize their personal ground to defend their ways of making a decision and course of action was eventually rejected by the court. General Chun and his peer General Noh served as a president in 1980’s and through early of 1990’s, but their glory just stopped there. As we learn, the final destination within this nature of public commission may go more proper if to respect the constitution and laws since any ultimate findings of a fit might sway. The conflict of interest also comes into a play if he or his peers embraced some of personal pursuit for the career success and welfare. Reference Cooper, T. (2012). The Responsible Administrator. San Francisco, CA: John Wiley & Sons. Hicks, D. (2013). Dignity: Its Essential Role in Resolving Conflict, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Laureate Education, Inc. (2008). Ethics and social justice, “Ethical Decision-Making” with Amanda Baker (approximately 12 minutes). 18 V. The Ethical Dilemma and Ethical Decision Making Model Introduction One of present controversy in Korea reveals that a chief of national prosecution offices (KPO) had resigned in response to his alleged wedlock child. He has been one of respected senior prosecutor trusted by a group of young manpower in KPO. Mr. Chae, now a popularity from the flak of majority party, Saenuri, and on some of split views from the public opinion, should wait for a completion of internal process on investigation and audit. His resignation was remitted and the Blue House endorsed a supervisory command delivered by the head of Ministry of Justice (KMOJ), Mr. Hwang. Dong-wook Chae, a week ago, announced his resignation in the press and public media right after the minister Hwang, formally a higher authority in ranks and files, decided to process an internal investigation about the alleged Chae’s ethical failure. The story actually has stirred over the month involving one madam, called Lim, who runs a prestigious salon for the socialization and fraternity among the high technocrats and wealthier class of Korea. KPO had been reputed as one of prime justice-promoting organizations since the dismantlement of militaristic nature of government around the early of 1990. They had once been rated by the media as a top public institution attracting the public credibility and trusteeship. They had deeply been engaged to eliminate the evils and harms within the power groups and wealthier class in Korea. One young prosecutor mumbled, “I have been proud of my organization because the injustice and public ailment therefrom was remedied on my own hand…This incident actually frustrated the organizational members.” Other man corroborated with his comment, “KPO may not be perfect if the political power intervenes. It, however, has been on public faith that it, at no exaggeration, worked effectively to correct the ‘past’ political power.” Situation, Factors, and Administrative Responsibility The context actually is complicated to encompass a scope of elements expressly and impliedly working (Laureate Education, Inc., 2008). The plain aspect of incident is an ethical misdemeanor allegedly perpetrated by the Chief of Prosecution Office (CPO), perhaps decades of improper relationship with the said madam and wedlock boy child. The practice of embroiled persons, in my personal experience, are not unusual to hold the kind of pattern behaviors that the prosecution officers have a tie and social coupling with a local pub or salon as the base for their informal contact and off time pleasure. If in worse, some of corruptive shade may exist ranging from the unpaid events of extravagant feast or gatherings and through a sexual brokerage prearranged by the interested private attorney, local potent or businessmen. Their interest may be unlawfully or unethically promoted against the proper administration of justice and professional rule of conduct required of public prosecutors. In the worst, some of prosecution officers may have a connection with the local gangsters to gather information, to subsidize a financial support, or to be engaged in more intimacy to a specific locale or potentials of crime network. Other factors in this kind of ethical issue are in need of consideration which is important to understand Mr. Chae’s objective and subjective responsibilities as well as the context of Cooper’s paradigm (Cooper, T., 2012). First, Chae was not the only officer to resign during his statutory term of two years, but twelfth in roll from a total of 18 since 1988. The statutory term was introduced to ensure an independence of KPO, a quasi-judicial institution, against the abuse or dereliction from the political power (Maccallum, G.C., 1993). Hence, the president or ministry of justice should 19 be restricted in dismissing a CPO at their will, but only statutory causes could justify it, which would be typical, of course and for example, a competence and health required to carry their duty, a level of crimes as provided by the law, and other basics. The bureaucratic line of authority was enshrined as a matter of public administration, but their intervention into any sensitive criminal cases of political nature was intended to be statutorily safeguarded by that very entitlement of mandatory terms. That was welcomed as one of wise institution by public in 1988, which was also grounded on the public trust about the separation of powers principle. Hence, Chae, like other predecessors, thought himself as a bulwark to defend an organizational identity or integrity and would like to maintain his good impression as a leader of KPO and as a courageous or impartial public prosecutor. Second, the presidential election, last year, was tainted in the first half year of Lady President Park from the onslaughter of unlawful meddling into the election process. She was a candidate from Saenuri, a ruling party, and the major opposition party, Democrats, seriously contended that the National Intelligence Service (NIS) intervened unlawfully and manipulated impermissibly the public opinion through their grapevines. Of course, it is not only an ethical requirement, but also a legal issue that the NIS and their officers should remain neutral and independent from the public election (Laureate Education, Inc., 2008). The Democrats, still rallying in the public street by installing a camp for the months stay of Han-gil Kim, a head of that party, had initiated conducting a congressional hearing about some of NIS’ issues. This initiative was actively pursued in the agreement of both parties, but had effected practically nothing with some of face-hidden witnesses, and insipidity of inaction and non-cooperation. Their filibuster or cause to passivism might be good on some legal justification, say, the national security or other public reason as specified in the statute, but the opposition party would be discontented with their defensive or non-engagement attitude. In this chain of power struggle, the prosecution offices decided to indict Se-hoon Won, a head of NIS, invoking its legal ground from a sensitive criminal statute, i.e., violation of the public election laws. This implies, as a matter of tone and attitude, that the prosecution office will go their way as insulated from a political discretion, and that they would be faithful to their job responsibility. Chae, thus, undoubtedly suffered from an ethical dilemma across many competing values and moralities (Cooper, T., 2012). As the issue is highly cardinal for the national integration as a matter of politics, he may waive a strict enforcement of law and apply some of acumen to avoid a couterpressure from its direct application of law. As the issue involves a petit offense as a matter of law, this option would surge very strongly in the course of ethical deliberation on his subject responsibility. The challenge to the legitimacy of president would bring a serious consequence while the application of laws matter at lesser extent about some amount of fines or its equivalent. He may hover around other alternatives, which include an invocation of other available criminal provisions, or some of inter-branch measure on the collaboration and cooperation. For example, the education and learning session about non- engagement principle in political matters and bureaucratic ethics could be used to circumscribe an usurpation of NIS and Blue House political elites (Hicks, D., 2013). He or other concerned group to cherish the rule of law concept within KPO may initiate a legislative workforce to restructure the inter- branch control and more effective system to operate ethically and lawfully as well as for a sheer preserve of bureaucracy independent from any swaying political influence. A scope of alternatives come to play, and could offer the ground of justification as a CPO in terms of subjective responsibility. This inner process is necessary and might later be called upon to respond to the congressional hearing or investigative context of process (Cooper, T., 2012). On the other hand, there are also a range 20 of factors involved in terms of objective responsibility and ethics as a CPO. Is the law applied correctly and could be sustained by the court? This is purely a technical issue of law, and centers at the heart of this organization’s cause to exist. What is the legislator’s intent to secure his term of two years in a statutory way? Are we entirely barred from any political discretion to keep neutral between the politically contending parties. Then the line of authority from the president, justice minister and through a CPO in ranks requires what extent of concession or compromise? How do the public laws on governmental employees, organizing and enabling statute of administration, the Act on KPO, and others interplay to guide his decision and course of conduct to handle this difficult ethical issue, i.e., more discretion v. strict enforcement of law. Third, the factors would become intertwined that may produce an amalgam of professional administrators which a lay person may not be easy, but leveled to be likely a neutral mechanic through the course of his decision and leadership action (2012). He rose to the top of KPO, but was reserved from the last administration led by President, Lee, M.B. He was not chosen by the Lady President, but his nomination was endorsed with the support and acclaim about his trustworthy career profile. He had been publicly introduced as a respected figure within the organization that the young generation of prosecutors admires as a paragon of their professionalism. The event has developed in a pattern for one sense, and unexpectedly in other sense. While a backdrop is not certain, but on the basis of public conjecture, a political group at the center and NIS may leak his private matters on the public media. Now he has turned to be a kind of scapegoat about his wedlock child and the quality of controversy involves an ethically faltering dimension from the normal compassion and traditional morality of Koreans (Laureate Education, Inc., 2008). He is a promising public employee who has been responsible to administer the national justice. The profession is viewed as a sanctity and generally of high level of ethics and moral standard despite being not compatible with that of clergy or priest. He is also considered mightier in power with other citizens that his impious and nasty behavior could well undermine his public impression and imagery of organization, say, KPO. He was unethical and the point exacerbated about some of influence and corruption from his mightier status. As a matter of course in the business of public media, reporters and editors are exalted to divulge this allegation based on the rumor in some cases and independent research on other cases. It suffices definitely to provoke the curiosity of public and the course seems certain to condemn the Chae’s case. He was pushed back to the corner and may be on groggy to become naught with nothing left (Hicks, D., 2013). He may highly wish to keep his good image on career and work profile, and likely detests the possibility to remain a gutless brass for his organization. The specters of Korea may approach to subject him to the kind of ordeal how you confront this dilemma. Inside his mind and on the standard of ethical code, his promenade in agony and exploration through the jumble of complicacies span extensively on the point of alternatives and consequences or prospects from his decision and course of conduct as in Cooper’s generalization (Cooper, T., 2012). The problem is serious in nature if to question and deprave fundamentally the basis of his morality and ethics as a public administrator. His alternatives, henceforth, may shrink to the simple option of whether or not he would resign and pomp his courage or a neutral and impartial carriage of job responsibility in his personal honor. On this front, he would not be best, however, if he simply decides to resign. That is principally because he has already responded by discrediting an accusation of wedlock child. Other important reason is that he would do better to maintain his current status and defend the statutory term. His instant reaction to resign would grow a more suspicion and distrust of public about the KPO. His 21 many predecessors, had to quit during his term, and this may lead him to sustain his position as the modality of organizational heads. He actually dropped this option, and began to defend his case through a media coverage. He later vowed to file the civil action on the claims of invasion of privacy or defamation. The press media counteracted to pressure by mentioning a gene test and other medical ways to prove his purity. In this progress, a moment of critical measure was rendered by his direct higher authority, justice minister Hwang that the department of justice will respond by processing the internal audit and investigation on the integrity and ethics of employees. His measure is grounded on the pertinent public laws about a supervision and command, but historically undocumented to initiate since the quasi-judicial role, i.e., criminal investigation and prosecution, has to be institutionally separated from the policy reason of KPO independence. KPO is generally responsible for the KMOJ, but a final say on the outcome of specific criminal case is institutionally a prerogative of KPO not to be meddled by the minister. His measure, in any way, was legitimate as a supervisory action, but might be acknowledged in other perception, which would be from young prosecutors about its impact as a pressure. They counteracted to investigate the minister Hwang, but the president and minister repeatedly confirmed that the matter is just the class of public employee’s ethics and sanctity required by the law (2012). Their intention is never to tame or control the independent authority of KPO, which should be on the conscience and law. This phase to any final process eventually led Chae to announce his resignation, but the president refused to accept it until the internal process of audit and investigation completed. The Ethical Decision Making Model and Chae’s Case This case shows a typical pattern of ethical dilemma involving a proper function among the intergovernmental organizations, independence of justice administration, and political influence. The Cooper’s ethical decision- making model stages in steps and feedback, which enables an extended scope of review and assessment for the respective ethical issue (Cooper, T., 2012). The idea involves a design approach, and the administrators, as C. Whitbeck proposed, can figure out what to do to deal with the ethical dilemma, as distinct from a normal attitude of merely making a judgment (2012). In application of the Cooper’s framework, we may have some of summaries on his respective element. Figure. Ethical Decision Making Model (Coopers) 22 Table. Application to the Chae’s Dilemma 1. 2. Perception of an Ethical Problem Perception of an Ethical Problem Defining the Ethical Issue Describing the Situation 23 3. 4. (a) rich odor of ethical corruption and infidelity on the basic social morality (improper relationship with a madam and wedlock child (b) political instability from the former administration, Noh and congressional hearing on the NIS, legitimacy controversy about the last presidential election and the NIS’s unethical support and alleged plot to intervene (c) criminal case and KPO’s unbent decision (d) suspicious leakage of private information and public controversy (e) announcement to respond with the civil action, KMOJ’s reaction to process the internal audit and investigation, resignation and pending context to continue by not accepting it (f) typical public issue of Korean judiciary and quasi-judiciary for its independence and proper administration of justice, De Ja Vue of many Chae’s predecessors to quit intermittently. 5. 6. Defining the Ethical Issue 7. 8. (a) Is it ethical and the ways of responsible administrator that Chae decided to apply the election laws in the indictment of NIS head, Won? How would it be working if he applied other available provision for the perhaps bigger cause of political stability? (b) Did he act properly and ethically that he stayed to maintain his office once the allegation stirred the public and raised a public distrust? (c) Is it proper and ethical to instantly respond with the public announcement of KMOJ to process the internal audit and investigation? Identifying Alternatives & Projecting Probable Consequences On the first issue, we may consider several alternatives-indicting as the law dictates, applying an acumen and political sense by avoiding an application of election laws. On the second issue, (a) it may be better to resign instantly if the suspicion has a strong ground and for its severity in the breach of ethical code; (b) he did well to stay since it is a kind of plot and must be subjugated by the public consensus about the traditional ways of leakage and public menace; (c) he did well to stay since his predecessors often happened to resign consecutively, which undermined the legislative purpose of statutory term and seriously tainted a public impression of KPO (Maccallum, G.C., 1993); (d) he did well to stay since his career and profile are high and merit to preserve from his followers. On the third issue, (a) he did well to announce his resignation instantly because KPO has to be insulated from the authority of KMOJ; (b) he did well to announce his resignation instantly because weeks of media coverage are enough to forge an awareness of the nature of controversy and KMOJ’s involvement made it firm about the public sensibility of political influence; (c) he did well to resign instantly since the public damage and debase had grossly aggravated from weeks of media coverage on this depraved unethical incident; (d) he should have continued on his job responsibility since he should respect the measure of higher authority and until his measure was completed; (e) he should have continued on his job responsibility since he initially avowed he did not have an improper relationship and the child is not his wedlock baby. Selecting an Alternative & A State of Resolution I consider his decision and course of action about the controversy and ethical dilemma would get better off provided if he instructed the public prosecutor in charge to act on the principles and law, but to defer a criminal prosecution on the statutory basis and also on the exculpatory clause because Won had been one of top bureaucrats, and contributed 24 much to the national interest, and because the offense was committed not by direct engagement in the alleged crime, but merely in the context of improper or lagged supervision (1993). In this line of thought, he also may consider a political instability if continued on the election laws. The conduct to counter a grapevine nature of disclosure and stay on his office seem proper given the context had been chronicled in the Korean society. This option could also be supported if it is fairly probable for the NIS or political core to intervene. If he plainly gets off his sacred job duty by resignation, it means that Koreans have no final resort to ensure their national justice and KPO’s cause to exist was highly damaged. He should have stayed even if KMOJ announced the process about an internal control. His instant reaction to announce a resignation evoked the public feel about his credibility and trust on his previous statement of innocence. He may see it cardinal or as a first priority to bar any exterior pressure or influence of KMOJ against KPO, but it is considered not to contradict the statutory mandate provided that KMOJ took a process to respond with the public turmoil arising from this surprising issue (1993). An organizational supervision about the integrity and ethics of public employees may be seen in a different light from the preservation of independent authority concerning the quasi-judicial function. Then the final outcome could be resolved by a gene test or findings of judiciary. The problem would arise from any continued media coverage, which cost a misleading and unnecessary consumption of public energy and time as a gossip or extended damage to the KPO’s reputation and honor of public prosecutors. Ways to eliminate this problem might be strived, for example, a faithful inducement to limit its coverage on public reason or others, and it could effect although not completely settled. That would be a proper expense to yield the best outcome in this serious circumstance. Then we have some improvements from the traditionally undesirable practices, a quandary of intermittent discontinuance of the KPO’s head, an unfounded allegation against the public figure, cult or myth on the KPO’s role, and public distrust or disinterest from any of manipulative or defrauded event. The alternative may restore an institutional interplay on the basis of law and statutes, public trust, and could enhance the right to know and serve in ways more than others. Reference Cooper, T. (2012). The Responsible Administrator. San Francisco, CA: John Wiley & Sons. Hicks, D. (2013). Dignity: Its Essential Role in Resolving Conflict, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Laureate Education, Inc. (2008). Ethics and social justice, “Ethical Decision-Making” with Amanda Baker (approximately 12 minutes). Maccallum, G.C. (1993). Legislative Intent/Essays Madison. WI: University of Wisconsin Press. 25 V. Differences and Similarities among the Human Rights Civil or Political Rights in the Comparative Viewpoint In a major classification, we have two groups of human rights which include civil or political rights and social rights. The civil or political rights are classic and an antedated group of rights which often are considered foundational through the democratic governance and modern constitutionalism. The attributes of these rights, among others, are (i) their competing virtue against a monarchy or dictatorship, (ii) principally driven to limit the governmental power (iii) negative rights from the abuse of governmental power (iv) to serve the new wealthier class of society (v) to champion the human dignity, autonomy and democratic virtues. Hence, the typology of this first generation of human rights actually has led the world political history to transform the feudal mode of rule to the modern form of Republicanism and democracy. The scope of rights are typical as we often encounter through the modern constitutions and international norms, which span over a writ system against the personhood, freedom of expression, and free exercise of religion, freedom to travel, economic freedom including the sanctity of property right and freedom of contract, equal protection of laws, right to privacy, and others (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Human Rights, 2013). These rights are typically placed in the bill of rights, notably in the State of Virginia and US constitution. A principled spirit enshrined in this set of rights are eminently pronounced in the preamble of US constitution or other classic declaration with such beautiful words, like inalienable, inviolable, god-bestowed, and etc. They projected the concept of classic liberty interest and often are considered to include the strands of natural rights. The rights in this group actually worked as a revolutionary thesis that should be achieved, and had been incorporated into the liberal constitutionalism. They are constitutional rights which deserve a special status as a matter of law. Plainly, they could not be repealed or negated by a mere majority of Congress or state legislature. A weightier process of constitutional amendment only could modify or abolish the ideas and requirements. In an in- depth theory, some of modern constitutional scholars argue that the fundamental liberty interest and human dignity could not be derogated even by the constitutional amendment (Hicks, D., 2013). They are the ground in most probabilities to conduct the constitutional review against a suspicious act or statute. Therefore, it has a root nexus with the idea of higher law or hierarchy tenet across a type of norms in order, constitution, statute or treaty, and executive orders. The federal system complicated this structure from the federal laws down through the state laws and in ranks across a type of norms. Practically, the judiciary had performed much role to protect the civil or political rights, nonetheless, it is a prevailing view across the jurisdictions that the rights in this kind are a guideline for all three branches of government to act and comply with. They could only entertain their power and authority under the sanctity of these human rights (2013). The concept, in this stand point of view, would relate with the separation of powers principle and tenet of limited government. The rights are enforceable as a technical matter of law concretely in the courtroom while the social rights are merely declarative or the kind of policy package the nation has to endeavor on programs or as a vision (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Human Rights, 2013). The rights are not goal-like one nor any moral standard, but can well be framed as a cause of action in a specific litigation. We often experience news stories which arise from the 26 human rights controversy. For example, the accused in the criminal proceedings may argue on a validity of death penalty statute on the ground of Eighth Amendment. White male students may argue on a violation of admission policy practiced in the public university provided if the policy infringes with his constitutional right of equal protection of laws by an unreasonable and affirmative treatment for minority groups. They share similarities that they are rights of public law. This means that the holders of these rights could claim against the state or federal government, and in theory or principle, could not intervene into the interpersonal affairs. This attribute may be revised in a social perception as we see in the state action theory. For the civil or political rights, we now consider that potential violators should not be confined to the government or public entity, but can, in a limited ambit and under the legal coherence in scheme, expand to some of powerful private enterprises or other organizations. For example, a discriminatory policy in the large shopping malls may impact on the society in the similar extent of influence. Then the shopping malls may properly be viewed, in the purpose of constitutional application, as something like the state in their function or activities. This constructive logic, then, enables that the human rights can be applied to the private entities. Of course, the social rights would be less friendly with the concept of application extension as a matter of nature. Social Rights in the Comparative Viewpoint Other group of human rights would be called social rights, which possess the nature and quality as distinct from the first generation of civil or political rights. The paradigm would have a different basis where each concept respectively corresponds with the liberal staticism and social welfarism. The social rights would differ in notion and attributes, which are (i) positive rights to claim an intervention and social programming of government (ii) cherishing a more focus on the social justice than a liberty interest, (iii) of collective and social nature for the common prosperity (iv) principally driven to expand the governmental roles (v) to serve a socially vulnerable class such as the working class, consumers, and post-modern context of individual realities. The class of rights would spread from the right to labor, humanly labor standard, right to the collective action, right to the basic education, right to the pleasant environment or decent housing, etc. In view of its practical operation, one illustration would serve as charted from the news paper stories. An issue of the child or prison labor would rise to the global attention. It is concerned of the labor standard, and hence entails a social right controversy. It also comes into play as one of international constitutionalism while the underdeveloped countries often perpetrate the kind of inhumane violation. As T. Talbott stated, however, we may see the issue likely as some of structuralist perspective and turn it within a possibly distinct context of compassion, culture, economic capacity of nation, and etc (2013). Therefore, an argument would be unwise if to compel a universal standard of labor as enforced by the developed countries. The problem also relates with the international trade issue which involves the WTO and ILO. The social rights have emerged to restore from a fundamental injustice and gross disparity which a laisez faire system of capitalist economy had brought in the 20 th century. Therefore, we often call them as a second generation of human rights which is in contrast with an 18-19 th prevalence on the civil or political rights. The idea of social rights was officially recognized in the adoption of 1949 Bonn constitution, and many new born states after two world wars have imported that way of dealings in shaping their national framework. It later developed in 27 the context of international constitutionalism in the leadership and initiative of United Nations. So we have two significant achievements to encompass both sphere of human rights, what are known the Universal Declaration of Human Rights (United Nations, 1948b) and International Convention on Economic, Cultural and Social Rights (United Nations, 1966). A constitutional status of social rights would differ in US, so that they had not been entitled to the place of written constitution and pursued in the leverage of US Congress and Executive (Maccallum, G.C., 1993). Notably, new deal programs ambitiously elaborated to rescue the national economy and promote social rights were framed within the series of federal statute. Some critiques would also raise a suspicion about its status as a right since they could not be claimed in the courtroom. Other reason to question its status lies in the tremendous expense and financial burden that make them at least be programmatic or package of idealistic state vision. A counter argument would point the similarities of both groups on this point as we see a positive aspect of state engagement in instituting a criminal justice system, costly public measure to ensure a liberty interest, and so. A Summary of Comparison From a foregoing brief on two groups of rights, we can illuminate a summary in view of the similarities and differences. First, it is similar that they concern human rights the standard of which centralizes on the concept of human dignity. Therefore, they are dynamic and evolutionary to respond with various factors, to say few, a political concept of society, circumstances and intellectual leverage of society (Donnelly, J., 2013). Therefore, the human rights student needs to see its attribute of dynamism and static aspect across the global jurisdictions. As a representative example in this concern, it is noteworthy that the constitution explicitly provides a concept of “unenumerated” rights. The rights set forth in the constitution are just illustrative that the policy makers can exercise their wisdom to define each specific human right. The right to privacy has had no language in the constitutional text, but a product of judicial wisdom. The right to die, right to know, and many others had been shaped and endorsed on this ground by the pertinent authority. Second, both enjoy a constitutional status except for few cases that could not be tarnished from the normal political power. In reverse, the governmental power is required to respect the spirit and command arising from the human rights purpose. A universal and regional covenant also confirms its status as fundamental and essential although the enforcement context would come meeker unlike the national dealings. Third, the idea of human rights presupposes a political community, and generally corresponds with then prevailing political virtue. Our dualism of human rights classification corroborates with this assumption. A liberal capitalism and social welfarism had driven to realize the two groups of human rights. Fourth, as a matter of definition and practical operation of those rights, there could we note a plethora of differences as described above. Reference http://www.un.org/rights/50/decla.htm http://www.amazon.com/Jack-Donnelly/e/B001HD40K0/ref=ntt_athr_dp_pel_1 28 Donnelly, J. (2013). Universal Human Rights in Theory and Practice. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Hicks, D. (2013).Dignity: Its Essential Role in Resolving Conflict. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Hunt, L. (2008). Inventing Human Rights: A History. New York/London: W.W. Norton & Company. Maccallum, G.C. (1993). Legislative Intent/Essays. Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin Press. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Human Rights. Retrieved Sep. 20, 2013 from http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rights-human/. http://www.amazon.com/Jack-Donnelly/e/B001HD40K0/ref=ntt_athr_dp_pel_1 http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rights-human/ 29 VI. The Attributes and Quality of Human Right Human Rights in the Preview What are human rights? How do we conceive them? We often hear of human rights and their social consequence in various aspect and levels, but we may become less definite what the words precisely denote. Someone may say the human rights are the kind of list in the bill of rights pronounced in the Constitution. Others may illustrate a political control or suppression against the free speech or press in China or North Korea. They, however, often have lacked an awareness if the African states’ children are starved and deprived of some of minimal standard to human livings. They also would become less attended that the middle Asian states have a unique culture to abridge the equal right of different sexes for the very reason that they have a religious justification for a different treatment. In the yardstick of western human rights group, their standard or practices would be inconceivable. In this impasse, a legal pluralism would probably be only way to understand their social dynamism. Therefore, the concept of human rights would have no clear cut to define in the aim of universal comprehension, but would be circumstantial and depends on the purpose of users. This leads to six or more families which are considered to describe the concept in most of influence through the history or political diversities (Hunt, L., 2008; Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Human Rights, 2013). Asked to give a summary form of definition, the human right is the scope of desired status of humans or some groups to be protected legally or by ways of the high extent of social force which often is deemed fundamental and essential to get along in any of human dignity. As they are fundamental and essential, they are high-priority norms as M. Cranston stated (2013). In this definition, we can derive attributes to entitle the concept as something of human rights. A Right: Human Rights as Static First, it is the right, not any of moral command or religious adherence to worship, which is viewed fundamental and essential (2013). Hence, the concept is presumed that the entitlement of human rights enable to claim the holders to pursue a legal protection, and through the vehicle of special institution. The ways to ensure them as a right may vary to cover a legislative enactment, judicial decision, or custom, but eventually leading to being part of the actual human moralities (Maccallum, G.C. , 1993). The statutory rights, in this ambit, are not human rights since they are neither fundamental nor essential. The right to tort damages, claims in many types of civil action, or administrative relief of industries against the foreign dumping practices would not be covered on this ground in view of the human rights concept. The human rights, therefore, often involve the kind of sensibilities found in the words, like sublime, idealistic, inviolable, or inalienable as we recourse the vintage of classic notion. The preamble of US constitution, the article 10 th of Korean constitution, Declaration of Universal Rights in 18 th France, and many new born constitutions in the 20 th century confirmed this approach utilizing the dealings as the heart of national administration. Since it is the right as a conceptual dealing, we need to investigate how they are realized in any of specific ways to enforce. Now most of nations have instituted the constitutional proceedings to review a violation of human rights by way of statutory provision like in Korea and Germany and by the case law as in US. In the United States, Marbury v. Madison pioneered to legitimate a constitutional review of the federal or state laws under the “case or controversy” requirement. 30 It is the right to protect an individual, but the group may be triggered as in the human rights consideration. For example, females would come into play concerning the domestic violence, reproductive choice, and trafficking of women and girls for sex work, assistance and care during pregnancy and childbearing, custody issues in the case of children, and the loss of historic territories by indigenous peoples (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Human Rights, 2013). Emergence as a Protesting Concept The constitutions as a matter of concern often rise in the context of national politics. The classic idea enshrined in the human rights is quite protesting in nature against the power of monarchy or from the fear of mob dictatorship. The constitutional drafters of US notably went that way that they saw the institution of human rights herald their first priority. It is rebellious idea and virtue to question the dominant governmental power. Therefore, the human rights concept is crucially intertwined with the assumption of higher law, national constitutionalism, political democracy and presupposes some of political community. Then it may be connoted in the purview of justified political morality and to identify a preexisting moral consensus. The concept of international constitutionalism had surfaced at the moment of UN inauguration and bitter reflection of the past two world wars. In our characteristics as a right, the international constitutionalism would not be tight unlike the domestic context of constitutional review, but we can witness notable achievements about civil or political rights and economic, cultural and social rights (2013). The regional organizations, Africa, Europe, and South America, also have been proactive in this area of concern (2013).Their extent of engagement would not be ensured by the judicial enforcement or concrete decree, but they are empowered to monitor, propose, and recommend. One cause for the action of UN security council, which would be a unique organ to enforce the mission of UN by a compulsory measure, arises from the violation of human rights. In this point of view, the international constitutionalism is not merely a paper tiger but could be supported by sanction or other forcible means. Human rights, as said, emerged as the ethos of protest against the abuse of governmental power. They had been, in the history and tradition, achieved in a revolutionary way and conceded in complicity with the higher law concept as advocated by the ancient common law lawyers, Sir. Coke and Blackstone (Hunt, L., 2008). Two notable incidents are the French and American revolution against then monarchy and exploitation. A British progress undertook a modest nature of evolution centering at the parliamentary system. A comparative view also shows this distinction that the Great Britain still has no written constitution besides the human right statutes while France respected the universal declaration of human rights as their essence of constitution. Other critical event as a protestant ethos of human rights perhaps would be the foundation of new world regime by inaugurating UN. An intolerable abuse of human rights in the two world wars and depraving cruelty, inhumane debase of human dignity drove to envisage some of international constitutionalism (Hicks, D., 2013). UN made several steps to realize that errand as mentioned above in terms of two classes of human rights respectively in 1948 and 1966. Therefore, the emergence of human rights often involves a shame status of politics and basic human dignity. They could be viewed in aspects not to be transhistorical, but minimal, or at least modest standards as Henry Shue pointed out (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Human Rights, 2013). They usually do not include a splendor of policy package, but could well tilt on the metaphor, for example, “how this can be tolerated as in the case of recent Syria?” 31 Static, but Dynamic into an Extension of Application and Scope Since it conceptually differs from the moral or religious command, the nature of right deserves more points of review about its legal status. The human rights are a public law concept which deals with the state and an individual. How to circumscribe the scope of individuals in terms of the entitlements or privileges also comes as a matter of constitutional interpretation. Is it to denote “people” as in the case of 18 th French declaration or “US citizen” encoded in many provisions of US Constitution? Are foreigners a beneficiary of constitutional shield in the issue of equal protection of laws? Korean constitutional court takes a view in general purview that the right to public office or election is limited to the Korean citizens. That is not the case when they face with an infringement of foreigners’ privacy right. The concept, then, is deemed a pillar to support the rule of law ideals against the abuse of state power. If the US Constitution has the nature of dual sovereignty between the federal and state governments, who is the addressee of constitutional dictate to protect the human rights also arises as a constitutional issue. The first ten illustration of bill of rights triggered the federal government, however, it could not reach the ambit of state sphere. This lacking, as we know, contributes to the contentious split of nation in the mid of 19 th century, and caused the civil war. The thirteenth and fourteenth amendments, and others were designed to cure this flaw that the mandate prescribed in these amendments was made imposed on the state power. By way of incorporation, the due process requirements, say, the privileges and immunities clause, could not be interfered by the state government. The contemporary problems about the constitution and human rights extend our deliberation on its nature. It contains, as we plainly encounter, many of sublime ideals to merit the extension possibilities as a guide or in a principled way (Reichert, E., 2011). In prolegomenon through its current status, it must be public and limited to react against the abuse of governmental power. Hence, they are not ordinary moral norms applying mainly to interpersonal conduct. On the other hand, the social evolution and increase of economic capacity allowed a new assessment or perspective how the constitutional affords could be received. It actually provides the moral standards which possess a universal appeal (2011; Donnelly, J., 2013). Furthermore, the classic liberalist view to check and balance as well as to limit the governmental power does not exactly fit within the contemporary passion. We often no longer need to be thrilled at any of tyranny or dictatorship unlike the circumstances of mightier Kings or revolutionary contingency. The practical problems had shown its extension of application that the private nature of contract might be invalidated from the human rights consideration. For example, is the private contract void if it includes a discriminatory clause against the minority? If answered no, how the response would change provided that the contract was enforced in the lower court, and appealed to the superior court? In the latter, the context may transform into a public matter since the lower court enforced such discriminatory contract for the black people. The court now can find an avenue to apply the constitution. Of course the ways or extent of discrimination should be weighed in given that it is private nature of relationship and submissive to the party autonomy. The case actually debated in the courtroom included a shocking arrangement to disable an access to some of residential zoning entirely by the rental agreement. In multiple factors of consideration, the courts now find a violation of human rights within the private sphere by applying the state action theory. This implies that the contemporary constitutions may be the kind of moral document in a limited context, allowing to meddle into some of private dealings beyond the rule of law concept. Therefore, it exists as moral and/or legal rights conceptually. On this 32 strand, it is interesting to see T. Pogge’s view that we can generate individual duties from human rights (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Human Rights, 2013). Dynamism in a Conceptual Understanding The initial phase of human rights henceforth evolved in progress to address the circumstantial needs and shape a new understanding of this concept. This means that it is dynamic to interact with the wake of history (Donnelly, J., 2013). Its quest to place it as the supreme status of national attention came from the bottom line, but had been conceded with the democratic rule in interplay and development. The government now accepted it as a first priority to respond that the negative cognizance of human rights turned to underlie the state duty to protect. Now the tone, “the government should not interfere with the freedom of individual,” changed that “the government has a constitutional duty to design and implement an adequate institution or policy to prevent the crimes.” The constitutional document would less be for a check and balance scheme, but could be a positive ground that the public administrators may recourse to base their policy choice or implementation. In this context, the human rights are not static that can be invoked only in the case of infringement or in the purpose to remedy the evils or harms. Given the passive quality of judiciary, however, this aspect of dynamism would range in a limited ambit that only can be addressed by the political branches, the US Congress or Executive (Maccallum, G.C., 1993). The separation of powers principle then factors circumscribing the span of constitutional dynamism. The court has no authority and resources to command positively to realize the constitutional virtues. The aspect of dynamism, as said and not perfect though, would differ if the court strives to connect a nexus in the purpose to apply the constitutional mandates to the powerful private entities. In the state action theory, the court tends on the modest stance in progressivism while it comes restrictively if the issue goes to the structure and function of government. The concept should be dynamic in its very aspect of human dignity (Hicks, D., 2013). The notion generally depends on the circumstances and status of society. A desired status of human condition would not be the same as centuries ago although the extent is not on a speedier turns like decades or years. A rapid transformation of society from the technological advancement, notably on the aspect of informative society, may shorten its turns. In any case, the desired human status may be conceptualized in responding to the evolution of society. This context can be evidenced from the generations of human right, i.e., first generation, second generation, and third generation. The waves of this new formulation may correspond with the political history, say, feudal, liberal paradigm of industrialization, and post-modern context of our livings. The feudal governance and social structure incur a serious injustice for the rising class. Their quest to restructure the system was collected into the bill of rights which reflected the fair share of new wealthier class. They then quested to freely express their idea, freely assemble to organize their political voice, and to be ensured of the property right and freedom of contract as well as personal liberty against the unlawful search and seizure, and so on. The second generation of human rights purported to react against the wrongs or social dilemma from the liberal capitalism. Now the human dignity became only to be restored by ways of social right concept (Hicks, D., 2013; Reichert, E., 2011). The right to labor, mandatory labor standard, right to the social benefit, and the kind of collective response were deemed ways to ensure the desired status of human condition. A predominant scope of them would cover the economic justice. The third generation of human rights advanced to ensure a decent living or human condition in this complex and challenging society. Then the class of rights requires a recognition and awareness as well as constitutional protection, which encompasses the right to decent housing, right to education, and right to the 33 pleasant environment, and others. On this point of dynamism involving the human rights concept, we also can note the attitude of concept and current practices, which span over the concern of human rights inflation, God-given natural rights, specific and problem-oriented ways of approach, feasibility to administer, too little or too much of international documents on human rights (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Human Rights, 2013). A Concluding Remark : State Administration and Social Progress I may, in addition, deliver two points which concern a dynamic nature of human rights or constitutionalism. As T. Talbott expounded, the human rights issue would be fairly nationalistic, and reflects a specific culture or compassion that entails the kind of structural issues as less susceptible of any universalistic generalization (2013). This idea has a root ground from the ancient thoughts and primordial intuition of communal primacy. This view is less done on the ages of enlightenment or human attributes that can be shared, which may go extreme to betray. The logic and argument, however, have strengths in the practical aspect. For example, the developing status of national economy may lead to a different level of human decency or the non-intervention policy as a matter of international politics may find their theoretical ground from his proposition. It also can be more adaptive to the concept of state sovereignty rather than the international commitments of human rights. This view also offers an easy way to account for the public emergency which threatens the life of the nation. The second point is why a plethora of contemporary constitutions have a written commitment about the second or third generation of human rights. The critiques argue that the scope of those human rights would not be enforced as a matter of legal right. This constitutional policy of direct incorporation would vitiate our understanding as a right. It is merely prescriptive to expose a vision or ideals that the state pursues, hence, is not a right in the strict sense. This goal-like dealings would blur the notion of human rights. This perspective, however, relates with the concept that human rights are negative rights, but it would be wiser to consider that the first generation also requires a positive engagement, i.e., creating an effective system of criminal law and property rights (2013). The US constitution would not be subject to this criticism, but it vastly matter with other progenies of contemporary global jurisdictions. The critiques also argue that they incur too much expensive cost to realize and their constitutional status is dubious, particularly for the non-enforceability. We may agree on this criticism as a public policy student, and probably find that the financial burden of poor government come at first. One idea could elicit the cause of this constitutional policy that the classic human rights also face with any same dilemma since the rights, as said, also can be afforded a constitutional protection by incurring costly institutions. Then there would be no explicit reason not to declare those rights as fundamental or essential. Reference Donnelly, J. (2013). Universal Human Rights In Theory and Practice, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Hicks, D. (2013). Dignity: Its Essential Role in Resolving Conflict, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. 34 VII. A Human Rights Violation and Workplace Introduction The public employees, as we learn, have a duty to respect the human rights in the course of execution of their position power. The kind of dealings to respond with the human rights violation may involve a court proceeding where the context would be posed and resolved in some more stricture of legal terms. The officers of government other than the judiciary, nonetheless, would shape their conscience and position ethics in the adherence of constitutional mandate. The congressmen would be specifically phased out in Article One, and their ambit as well as course of work demand, organization and other key features would be delegated by the Constitution. The president is prescribed, in a direct way of constitutional provision, “he or she is obliged to faithfully execute the laws and…” This mandate, as a matter of logic and line hierarchy of Executive, would be pertinent to a scope of Executive officers. Public organizations other than the government may not be immediated to the constitutional mandate, however, we can see high chances to be regulated by the Constitution, as we see in the cases of affirmative action embroiling the public universities and public bidding. Other private organizations also may not be complacent with their status out of the force of constitutional vision. The reason would be that the state action theory may apply to defame their business reputation and can incur a loss from the damages or others. This awareness, in other aspect, conforms with the ethics of business, entrepreneurship, and social justice. It would be desired from the concept of state action theory that scholar practitioners would bring the social change (Laureate Education, Inc, 2013). Three of the Prison Mistreatment I like to brief on three cases of human rights abuse in the workplace, and present some thought in the assumption that I was charged with the job responsibility at matter. The cases involve a prison setting in which the prisoners are treated unduly in violation of human rights. Korea, in the ethos and passion from a Paris initiative, instituted the National Human Rights Council (NHRC), whose role and power of institution would be similar, in its nature and extent, to HRC of UN (Universal Declaration of Human Rights, 2013). It collects the events of human rights violation, reviews their profile, advises on a correction and alternatives, publish the case books as well as comment and opinion. The human rights violation about the prisoners are serious that reported 35 percents of the whole complaints filed within NHRC (Mun-Wha Daily, 2013). This accounts for one case among the whole of three in math, which deserves a nickname of prison, a “worst devil” about the human-rights public moral. One prisoner, aged around his twenties, was appalled at the sudden demand of body examination when he was escorted to the prison upon a completion of criminal interrogatory in the prosecution offices. The prison officers told that it is an internal regulation to conduct a physical examination when the prisoners came back from outside. He ordered to take off a prison uniform in the public place where other persons are present. Mr. Kim pleaded that the process could be enforced in other confidential place, but was rejected (2013). So he was compelled to expose his body as undressed entirely in the public vision, which includes female prisoners. The context of process imposes an extent of personal shame and debase of human dignity, which caused to file a complaint. Other prisoner, who was aged around forties and now released from the prison, experienced a 35 cruel measure from his altercation with the inmates. The prison authority ordered a handcuffed status of two hands, his upper body being tightened in ropes, and eventually was delivered into a solitary room (2013). This violent measure incurred an aftermath of hospitalization from the callous wrists and fingers. Another prisoner, who was in his forties, was served an inhumane and cruel decision that his petition to an adequate medical care for his chronic illness of bone disk was denied. He suffered from a serious pain and was disabled to walk nor move. The medical assessment that he should be afforded a systemic treatment for one year failed to effect. According to the statistics published by NHRC, the prison context of human violation is a most popular cause to bring a petition. Among 56,415 reported in the section of public institutions, the prison explains 35.3%, 19,932 in number which is most notorious. The police and its supplementary facilities came second in rank that 12,038 cases were reported (2013). The third in row is a public mass camp for the homeless and social protection services (9,071) and the fourth in other unclassed categories of government (5,630). In the last year of 2012, 1,737 cases were reported to claim an intra-prison human violation while the number never reduced this year. One officer of NHRC commented, “The reason for an abundance of human rights violation in this facility would lie in the nature of institution as well as constant monitor as well as on-site activities by the NHRC” (2013). Assessment and My Viewpoint The human rights abuse within the prison exhibits a good point of consideration about the role of public officers and concept of public value. This is because that the nature of public administration requires pursuing a public utility in the sacrifice of private or personal interest. This focus would well be churned in Bentham’s philosophical works extensively (Postema, G. J., 2006). His episode about the dilemma arising from a highwayman and housebreaker shows a hard-reconciled tension as well as pleasure and pain, which are a primal point his thesis begin with. His wry wit can well be understood if the public service is deserving of the kind of sinister persons. It is an irony, however, that the public administrators are required to execute their role and responsibility for these vile people and in conformity with the liaison or network concept as arranged to administer the maximization of happiness (2006). It leads to a free riding injustice, the concept of which can also apply to the contemporary cases. For example, we consider a more due framework about the extent and scope of intellectual property in the international plane. The developed countries argue on a more extent of legal protection while the underdeveloped ones countered. The sense and concept of justice differ that the developed countries impute a free riding accusation for their opposites. In the precept of Cicero, the rulers and public administrators seek a justice, which could only lead to a human solidarity (2006). The state of human solidarity also can only be procured in the event that the private and personal interests coincide with the universal interest according to the Bentham’s calculation. This interplay would be only an avenue that the humans can find a pleasant public life provided if they are any political or social animal. It controls and determines the pleasure and pain, and may influence a final state of happiness as we pursue in the context of definite human goals. 36 That said, we consider a prisoner’s predicament and our personal state based on the fact brief as disposed above. Some may get instantly conflagrated to elevate the standard of prison regulation. The others may see the treatments deserving since he or she is a sinister actor in contradiction to the overwhelming public cause. The four elements, as envisioned by Bentham and composing the universal interest, would not contravene this view, which are a “maximization of subsistence, abundance, security, and equality” (2006). Their status as a prisoner would well be responded with his “fallback principle,” such that the standard would be lowered to suffice four elements (2006). It satisfies the condition that an equality and security would be ensured among the prisoners themselves. Their claim to seek the same status as his law abiding neighbors on those four would come never merited. The points of focus in these cases could be posited in the light of “centre of gravity” argument. The interests to be weighed in involve a sensitive area of personal privacy or right to the basic health and humanly living within the controlled context of prison administration. They might be intervened with less a persuasive reason or deprived implementation not carefully designed about the abuse on human rights interest. The physical examination could be delivered in a confidential area or in decency without costing much. The handcuffed status, particularly on both hands, and upper body in ropes, would make a prisoner appear like the beast immediately captured and delivered into a public shelter. The confinement into a solitary room might be sufficient to prevent any post violence problems. It also can be put to improvement if the prison authority respected the health petition more generously. Reference Laureate Education, Inc (2013). Ethics and Social Justice "Human Rights: Applications" with Amanda Baker (approximately 8 minutes). Mun-Wha Daily, Sep. 24 2103, p. 10. Seoul, Korea. Postema, G. J. (2006). Interests, universal and particular: Bentham's utilitarian theory of value. Utilitas, 18(2), 109-133. Universal Declaration of Human Rights.Retrieved Oct.1, 2013 from http://www.ohchr.org/EN/UDHR/Documents/UDHR_Translations/eng.pdf. http://www.ohchr.org/EN/UDHR/Documents/UDHR_Translations/eng.pdf 37 VIII. The Utilitarian Theory and Human Rights Violation Introduction The primal strand in the public utility or utilitarianism recourses the human elements, in which many theories, tenet, and polity would undertake as a niche of intellectual persuasion and account. For Bentham, the pleasure and pain are a destination and point of shipment to project his extended concern and philosophical dialectics (Postema, G. J., 2006). His discourse and systemic contention to explain and forefront an inchoate liberalistic society, later highly influenced the work of Mills in terms of political moralities and political sociology. Both are generally considered most profound authorities to marshal intellectually the ethics and public virtue of English speaking concept which had been developed and adapted by the elaboration of Rawls in the twenty century. A revolutionary ethos and turbulence actually dismantled an injustice from Ancien Regime, but the practical consequence had to suffer from the emergence of Napoleonic contingencies in Europe and interstate contention or incongruence leading to the civil war in US. New philosophical wave has been received as inviolable or inalienable, however, how it could be practically achieved posed a challenge to the scholars and public authority. In view of Cicero’s precept, a human solidarity, an equivalent of justice for the rulers, could only be settled on “societas et communicatio utilitatum,” the community or public utility in modern words (2006). This concept would be compatible that the humans are a living creature within the community and only could possibly exist in that context. That said, the human elements now turn to have a meaning in the context of interplay with the community and public. Humans can only be solid in the eyes of such strong Rome and its state theorist within this concept of justice, and their true interests can be negotiated or delivered. In the Napoleonic errand, the public administration has been made rather solid when a modern major genre of national codes was erected and applied in France and the conquered lands, i.e., civil, criminal, two procedurals to serve the substantive rights and duties, as well as administrative law. It is a notable achievement to substantiate the new wave of bourgeois public or democratic virtue. Nonetheless, his background and ways of militaristic imagery had confused his mission to be politically interrupted. His contribution to advance the democratic concepts is assessed positively from the historians. Particularly, his vision and realization of new public virtue into five major national codes are now followed by both of major legal traditions notwithstanding the common and civil law distinction. While the constitution was not declared in an independent scheme, the universal declaration of human rights serves that purpose and more classic or deemed fundamental given no nomenclature to dress it up as a constitution. The new continent began their public administration on the basis of federal constitution, but the federal power was contested in the initial phase. The scope of federal administration would expand and be adjusted to serve the public value and humanly government or public administration. As we note, the commerce clause and contract clause as well as the necessary and proper clause offer the ground to deliberate both standing concerns. A Survey of Basic Tenets on the Utilitarian Theory As a pioneering engineer for modern public administration, Bentham’s concern should rise involving the concept of universal interest (2006). What is universalism? It, as a matter of nature, takes the ways to keep on the logic, tone and metaphor from the kind of fundamentalism, rationalism, and idealism. In order to be universal, it has to be reasonable and also should be idealistic to possess the quality as a universal appeal. It also could serve if 38 to ground on some of fundamental dealings that the mankind could commonly share. Then, he would be a good student who borrowed the concept and theory from David Hume or German idealists. His moralities argument had suffered from multifaceted challenges on the civilian quest for the personal or private interest, which should well be expected from the aftermath of civil revolution. This context can be evidenced from his words, “the world now is fleeting and rare,… insanity” (2006). He also explored the context of international politics in his book titled “Constitutional code,” and exposed a sentiment in his critique of Spanish colonialism, “Typically one’s recognition of this commonality produces a sense of solidarity : by this very community of interest is produced a community of sympathy” (2006). Hume’s influence, as from “Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals,” would be a necessary condition to develop his humanistic public philosophy, but not a sufficient condition leading to his tremendous contribution for the modern substance of post- revolutionary administration. As we consider, his view also influenced the Weberian concept of practical capitalism and bureaucratic practice while the work of M. Weber, as we see in the ethics of bureaucracy, explored an extended scope of factors, which cover the social custom, religion, compassion and tradition beyond a raison or principles (Murphy, A., 1998). In any case, the perception of Bentham would be more urgent and immediate to bridge the rising quest of civilians and dilemma of how to shape a political sociology or political moralities. Therefore, his nexus comes forward with the communal consequentialism and may develop into the compositionalism as the kind of end state that the public administrators envisage. The social welfarism and individual welfarism may correspond practically with his basic exposition between the universal and private or personal interest. He has some aspect of distinction between the private and personal interest, and his narrative massively relied on the scale of interest given his errand on the public good or utility (Postema, G. J., 2006). So the personal interest may come more trifling than the private interest while both are merged or adjusted to the grand scale of universal interest. He saw that an individual happiness can only turn legitimate or possible to coincide with the universal interest. This ideal comes rather authoritatively and as structured between the public and private dualism (Audard, C., 1999). First, he waived much of contemporary understanding about the role of education. Rousseau and other European thinkers focused on the importance of education and could be corroborated from the work of John Dewey, one of eminent public thinkers from the United States. Second, he also overlooked the potential civil power particularly within the traditional operation of civil laws. His book dealing with the civil code discourse connoted implicit difficulties along with the civil justice on economy and personal status. While we consider an importance of these strands in this contemporary public administration, this may bring his work on a formalistic philosophy, but it is undeniable to proffer a vertebrate organism of it (Murphy, A., 1998). Then his dilemma may revolve about the fundamental confrontation between the equality and utility (Postema, G. J., 2006). Everybody would claim an equality to be static in view of the post-revolutionary imperative. It poses challenges in leading a social or economic reproduction. Nobody would do more, which means just a sacrifice to labor or submit to the public service. It merely would be a heroic sacrifice that Bentham saw a kind of worst or trifling scenario. The equal liberty or equal happiness in the Bentham’s word, other than equality, would engineer their motive to labor given the new capitalistic economy. For example, the equality, which might be graced from the Christianity under the God, now turned on the new political and economic arrangement. They now can claim the property rights and freedom of contract. This emancipated a bourgeois class, however, should be 39 reconciled from the constant tension between the public and private interests. His alternative to deliver this tension comes from the concept of utility or public utility. His analysis draws on the basics of us so as to realize a happiness, which he also perceived as a sovereign master of human motivation and behavior. Therefore, his dealings may culminate in Chrestomathia, which churned on the ideal of public welfare (2006). His junction also could not be compromised in any plain version with the kind of ideas, monarchy or oligarchy since it, in normal conditions, contradicts his ideal of greatest number of happiness. His adherence with the happiness conception never is an abstract nature, but could be substantiated with his words, “greatest equal happiness” (2006). In order to find a proper principle to achieve this end, he has not neglected to deal with the problem, such as identification of interests, genus et differentam, the centre of gravity, and etc. His philosophical disposition on these points are fairly echoing for the modern public administrators. We often consider that a superior public official is competent to identify the conflict of interest involved in the specific public agenda or sensitive issue. They also need to possess a talent and concern about the genesis and differences involved in the object, challenges, issues, projects, and public programs. Then his frame of argument turns again on the tenet between the universal and particular interest in the Book of Fallacies, which he perceived as challenges against his concept of public value, what he called a sinister sacrifice or interest. He saw a constant tension and implacable hostility, and an individual only could maximize his sum of happiness to conform his private or personal interest to the universal one. He, however, degraded the heroic sacrifice since it results in yielding all the instrumentality of felicity and even the life itself (2006). He saw it mere altruism which is neither welcomed nor in comport with his tenet on the sacrifice to the universal interest. His adherence to sacrifice for the universal interest is called upon the premise that the individual has a share in cause of sacrifice and has a genuine basis on the individual ground or human attributes, such as felicity or pleasure, and others. Therefore, he cherished an individual aspect while he stressed on the public cause or reason. This way of approach reflects then dominant assumption on the life, who was endowed of the right to pursue a happiness in the preamble of US constitution. The idea also endorses the role and extent of dominance of civil society between the “subject many” and “ruling few” as well as their protestant ethics or conviction on the revolutionary spirit. An individual, now in a new framework of politics, is the person to be motivated in their interests, which would be prurient or commercial. He was shrewd to look at this aspect, so that he never overlooked the genesis of human or individual. His idea is fairly liberal and democratic, as we see in Kamikaze in the Second World war. The incident, of course, was militaristic and serves the totalitarian cause of imperial Japan. Therefore, the concept of “compensation” arose to bridge the civil interests and public authority. Kamikaze had no basis of individual interest who was pushed forward to sacrifice their lives. Bentham also staggered critically about the aristocracies which he would be reluctant to endorse on his theme of public value. The politicians, landed aristocracy, clergymen, and legal elites were no longer the main of social or economic reproduction, who were idle and predatory (2006). The oligarchy or well structured classic society was seen largely failed to correctly reflect the social justice which came contrary to maximize the greatest number of happiness. In perversion, his illustration involving a highwayman and housebreaker shows the context of social injustice and well provoked a free ride’s calculation. He hardly found any point of public utility for this group, which would be yielded for normal citizens from the public service, such as national defense or policing. In this case, the fallback principle, a close concept of specified justice, could be applied to ensure a maximum happiness. Three Cases of the Human Rights Violation 40 In the application work of Bentham’s tenet, I like to illustrate three examples of human rights violation in the purpose of ranking them on the basis of maximum public utility. That might not be less accurate in a strict terminology of human rights violation, but was drawn in the close context (Universal Declaration of Human Rights, 2013). In the militaristic nature of Korean government during the early of 1980’s, Jong-cheol Park, who was a college student at that time, was tortured to death, and stirred the public sensibilities and antipathetic reaction. The government, at that time, was of hard nature to control and overwhelm the civil society. Korea was then one of underdeveloped countries, and the environment of dictatorship could be fertile. There had been a scope of public cause for the central control and tightened context of rule, for example, development of the national economy and assurance of the social welfare and justice, national security from the aggression of North Korea, and so (Laureate Education Inc., 2003). The incident involved an outrageous conduct of government, specifically the police branch of anti-communist team. Mr. Park was just a suspect, who was allegedly engaged in the public demonstration to restore the democracy of nation and legitimacy of government. The atmosphere of society was well tamed and structured, though questioned seriously on the ground of its legitimacy, under the ideals of national stride both in economy and national prestige in the international community. A limited scope of students in vigil and civil monitors occasionally mobilized a public campaign and street demonstration to react against the undemocratic practice of government. The opposing politicians might have a link with the progressive group of society including the college students. The incident led to the national controversy, and its consequence was serious with the series of protest and picketing in the public streets, and public rally of mass people. The initial response of government was ironic and bought a public outrage that the fact was fabricated. They alleged no torture, such as water boarding, electronic stick, nor application of irresistible physical force from several of torture technicians. This allegation actually proved false from the testimony of one conscientious clergyman, and all the truths were revealed with the aid of public media and civil activists (2003). This incident, which occurred in 1987, conflagrated a public cause of June march of Korean citizen, and led to the consequence adopting a direct election of president. The constitutional reform was realized to restore the separation of powers principle, five years term of presidency, endorsement of privacy right, and others. Most importantly, a superficial method to elect the president in the stadium by an highly dependent electoral body, which, however, represented the national cause monopolized by the ruling party and practically governed by it, was replaced so as to ask a direct will of nationals. The concept might be formalistically similar to the electoral college system of US, but the practical operation would come closer to the communist mode of secret election. One other example would rise from the present context of Korean politics. Lady President Park once promised to design a national welfare system for the aged people. His promise contains the policy that the people over 60 in age would be entitled to 200 US dollars on an annual basis unconditionally. It would be idealistic, and serves a universal interest in the Bentham’s calculation (Universal Declaration of Human Rights, 2013). It now became floated away in the face of tough national treasury. Her administration may well buy a public antipathy since the promise was made during the presidential election and should be kept. The reaction could also be organized in the opportunity of opposing party, and still contended in the National Assembly. This year’s budget will likely face a stiff response in the end of this fiscal year, and may have high chances as usually charted with such physical confrontation in the floor. A physical confrontation and violence is practically an equivalent of phillie buster in Korea. The nature of issue comes ironical as similar to the US case, named 41 “Obama healthcare.” The direction would be perverted, however, that Korean government, in this case, initiated to reduce the welfare benefit. Lady President presented a public apology for her breach of promise, but her action would be supported by concerned intellectuals and professional policy makers. That is because the government frankly would mislead the public if to keep her promise. The debt of government became tremendous and her promise requires an excessive budget without any economic impact to breed the national economy. A disappointment of social minds and ill consequence on the deprived class, however, would be obvious. The last example would be a Mr’ Chae’s ethical violation and its consequence, which has covered months of media coverage, his retirement, and intervention of supervisory body, say, the Minister of Justice and President. As a chief prosecution officer, he was accused of his wedlock baby while he may consider himself as one of scapegoat cases. He may have been disgruntled with the attitude of public media, or personally apprehended with any of political plot against the carriage of his official responsibility. He may esteem himself as to lead the KPO impartially and had a belief of sanctity on the institution’s quasi-judicial quality of public power. He would like to execute a statutory term as the kind of modality unlike his predecessors. He also may deplore an invasion of privacy as a lawyer, and may now have an awareness about the serious consequence from the leakage of private information. He also would consider his status as a public figure and may weigh in factors to be in pertinence. He actually resigned yesterday, and held a public memorial to honor his retirement. His plan is to withdraw a civil action, yet to keep on his promise about the gene test. However, it is dubious whether it could be realized since the consent of biological mother should be acquired. A Possible Rank of Three Cases in View of the Utilitarian Theory Three examples described above would involve the human rights violation. In the first case, we can note a serious nature of human right violation patterned through history (2013). The torture is just the point of focus that the modern civil movement triggered to abolish. It relates with the fundamental civic virtue to ensure against, and has duplicated as a constitutional mandate across the scope of global jurisdictions. The third example also elicits the kind of confrontation between the liberty interest and public cause. The privacy right is classic, but comes into a legal province rather belatedly in the new frame of modern virtue. The second example involves the human right to any entitlement of social benefit or privileges. In the purview of Bentham’s, we hardly rank them in any order concerning “pleasure and pain,” the greatest number of happiness, equal happiness, and maximization of public utility (Postema, G. J., 2006). That is particularly because his idea was never intended on any math or quantification. This is not to say that the quantitative analysis should drop or comes meaningless. It could base well in force to persuade on the policy strengths or urgency to implement. However, I mean that it possesses a quality element as we see in his thesis, the “center of gravity” (2006). That aspect is important particularly because the policy makers often face with the issues and dilemma of multifaceted and complicated status. A social passion, tradition, administrative custom, prevailing concept of politics, morality, and many others beyond the economic factors of cost and benefit would come into play. Therefore, the intuition and instance also has some prongs to perceive the challenges and shape the policy response to address the harms or evils. That is particularly because the “pleasure and pain” as well as the concept of happiness as a measure of public utility are ultimate as we can share, yet not to be definite as a matter of quality. I am not sure how we can finely rank the above three. But I suppose that we may agree if it could be first, second, and third in order if we 42 exercise our intuition. His point about the centre of gravity would tell much to leave the last two behind. Bentham’s concept of universal interest also plays to make the first case more serious and safeguarded (2006). We may well conceive a fear and would fail if to let such practice to go in that way. Bentham’s four prongs of public value also corroborate that a security or maximization of subsistence would be fundamentally depraved in the first case as compared with the last two cases. An equality and abundance come to matter in all three cases, but come poised in the balanced consideration. For example, the equal liberty claimed by Mr. Chae would be legitimately traded off in the public interest. He is a public figure which is an enabling factor for some extent of public disclosure. The equal liberty claimed by the aged people of Korea would have a stronger profile than Mr. Chae’s case. However, that is also amenable to the discretion of government and other competing virtue of Korean Republic. The maximization of subsistence interest may rise in the second case, but it is dubious how much the policy can lead to the after-years lives in peace and affordable subsistence. Abundance also is a very difficult concept to weigh in any definite direction on our examples. Then we now apply his tenet of universal and private or personal interest where the individuals should comply with the former in the maximization of his happiness. If the human rights violation were to be resolved in other way, the private interest and universal interest would comport among another. On this test, the outcome would be similar that the first case only can ensure definitely to share both concepts of interest. In the second case, we see the universal virtue of social welfare, but could be well rivaled from other kind of public interest. The third case would go into a jumble of different values across the culture, social attitudes, legal theory, custom and intellectual divergences. Given the universal interest comes not in any clear context, the third case would be ranked in the last. A Concluding Remark His idea is foundational in theory and tenet, and can persuade many challenges and issues to be resolved. His contribution would convert a youthful idealism into a practical ground with the weighty responsibilities of public organizations. Our lesson also lies in his view about the nature and function of public administration, for example, “liaison” uniting them and “public felicity.” He also recognized the hard nature of public cause or engagement in contrast between a “chain of iron” and “rope of sand” (2006). Although the private interest is only to be endorsed if to coincide with and share the universal interest, there often would be so a strong of private interest like the iron, and the public role would likely search a rope of sand. As we acquiesce in his dealings, “community of interest” and “community of sympathy” in the Spanish America or the concept of “alliance and partnership,” it might be a product of influence from the colonial experience, hence, international in quality, but also coincides with the national dilemma, for example, civil actions in the courtroom between “procedural and substantive.” How to design the civil procedure in the end of speedy, fair and impartial administration of justice would be a concern of public felicity, however, secondary and merely supportive to the serious contention about the property right or private interests. One example could be a former form of GATT, 1947 GATT, in the contemporary international politics, in which the GATT council was relegated as mere a “liaison office” without any decisional power. In any case, his idea is actually ambitious and persuasive to cultivate the public officers, as we agree on his four elements of public utility, i.e., maximization of subsistence, abundance, security, and equality (2006). This quality can immediately subordinate the right, a most enhanced form of private interest, serve the proper ends of government, and comport with the foundations of civil law, and are considered as constituents of universal interest. 43 Reference Audard, C. (1999). Anthologie historique et critique de l'utilitarisme, tome 1 : Bentham et ses précurseurs (1711-1832). Paris: Presses Universitaires de France – PUF. Murphy, A. (1998). Reason, Reality, and Speculative Philosophy. Madison WI: University of Wisconsin Press (1996). Laureate Education Inc. (2003). Ethics and Social Justice "Human Rights: Applications" with Amanda Baker (approximately 8 minutes). Postema, G. J. (2006). Interests, universal and particular: Bentham's utilitarian theory of value. Utilitas, 18(2), 109-133. Universal Declaration of Human Rights, Retrieved Oct. 3, 2013 from http://www.ohchr.org/EN/UDHR/Documents/UDHR_Translations/eng.pdf. http://www.ohchr.org/EN/UDHR/Documents/UDHR_Translations/eng.pdf 44 IX. Equality and Distributive Justice Some Thoughts on the Concept of Equality The concept of equality is dressed in a different ethos and understanding in history and tenets. It certainly does not connote the kind of identity or nor cohere the objects in any identical finding. It is, therefore, a relational and social concept, which is directed to the human beings. A morality-based equality does not compel to treat the objects same, in general tense, but similar, and complete or absolute equality might be envisaged, but either practically hardly achievable or deemed undue to address the equality challenge. Hence we consider the general and specific context of justice which presumes the idea of distributive justice and can respond to an argument on equality. As a modern critique, R. Dworkin lodged his viewpoint of disagreements about the proposition of absolute equality (SEP: Equality, 2013). He rather cast a competitive strand drawn from the value concept where the equality quest should be contested in a respective province of society. It is interesting given his scholarly pursuit as a legal philosopher. He is generally considered to bridge the common law tenet and ethos with explaining some of coherent uniformity and possibility of governance. As we are aware, an ultimate purpose of law underlies the liberty and equality within the subject. These concepts would be sublime and enjoy a sanctity that undertake, however, a scope of realistic challenges. Particularly, the pragmatic measure and perception from the common law lawyers like to substantiate them to expand the rule of law ideal in the hybrid or multifaceted layer of international structure of governance (West, C., 1989). In his framework, the concept of value rose to center in penetrating a new wave of demand in the international politics. The legal pluralism can also be projected in his ambit and law elements to enable the picture of ideals as we note in his treatise, titled the Empire of Law. So the value, in his thesis, plays leading us to a legal plutocracy and legal pluralism, which opens the eyesight to the realistic posture of our legal system. Then, his perception of equality would not be one of formalistic generalization, but enriched a scope of distributive justice to the emerging diversities via emancipation and post-colonial new republics on earth. In a most comprehensive context of equality moral could be encapsulated in the nomenclature of egalitarianism under which a tack of principles or specifics would be proposed, contended, argued, and debated. In approaching the concept of equality, there are two ways in deals as a matter of intellectual strand, which would cover a descriptive equality and prescriptive one. This view was proposed in most extent by Oppenheim, and accounts for the realities of equality narrative (2013). The descriptive equality concerns the kind of story telling practically shed in our realities, which also could be afforded in an enhanced application in the tradition of common law jurisprudence and post-modern context of intellectual exposure. The ways of approach can lead to an inductive reasoning practiced on the attitudes of common law judge. They never mind to become a story teller to expose a lengthy fact about inequality or harms on injustice. Of course, their final destination would not be merely descriptive so that they analyze the facts to find a most proximate precedent to be applied. In rare cases, they undertake a solitary role to shape his or her own rule given that he fails to find a binding precedent. The context of judge-made law begins with the concern of descriptive equality to finally produce a forest of prescriptive equality. It may be compiled in order, as in the Restatement, to respond with the civil code and prescriptive justice or equality. The ways of approach would be quite opposite in essence concerning the civil law tradition, which, 45 nonetheless, sees an extent of convergence in the practical viewpoints. The prescriptive equality would come, in the first, as to the statutory requirements or provision. A deductive reasoning would be undertaken to apply the law to the facts presented. A phase in the intellectual deliberation, in any case, may often be resolved in tertium comparationis to allow a distinct preserve of jurisprudence as in other area of disciplines. This view can also expand to other disciplines that we often class them in the inductive and deductive formalities (Jeffreys-Jones, R., 2013). The sense and attitude about this point may pose a grand disagreement between the creationists and evolutionists in the past years. We may reflect on our intelligent strand as a public policy student, which would also be advisable given an increasing number of public laws, hence, in a form of statute, as well as needs to refer to the case law in dealing with the public agenda. In consideration of the equality concept to be realized in public administration, we may deliberate on morality and justice in general and distributive justice in particular (SEP, 2013). Actually the policy environments would be constituted from actions, persons, social institutions, and circumstances, which drives us on how to pillory certain inequalities. We may defer to an ethical individualism, but keep on his or her voluntary action and can allot the responsibilities, who would be a policy subject. In the course of weighing, we can learn the general and specific concept of equality as Rawls and Roe expounded. We may revert, in some cases, to the basic about the formal equality and presumption of equality. Within this province, we are required to treat like cases as like (2013; Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, V.3. 1131a10-b15; Politics, III.9.1280 a8-15, III. 12. 1282b18-23). In view of moral equality, the humans or policy subject in the public administration should deserve a same dignity and respect as founded in the stoicism, new testamentary of Christianity and a scope of religious branches (also for example, Déclaration des droits de l h́omme et du citoyen of 1789). The presumption of equality would be sustained in various rationale and scholarly propositions, i.e., relevant reasons approach by Williams, a conception of symmetry by Tugendhat, default option by Hinsch, and even for criticism of the presumption of equality (2013). Also one useful tenet involving the equality concern can serve the foundation of our governance structure from the ancient times through the present context. The idea is about a proportional equality as meditated by Aristotle. The concept then comes applied beyond the moral aspect of equality by dealing with a numerical and proportional dimension (2013: Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, 1130b-1132b; cf. Plato, Laws, VI.757b-c). Therefore, it turns to possess the quality of being incorporated as the political ground, a virtue of head count in the equal election and governance measure, involving the proportionality concept, so that it enables a hierarchy and inegalitarian treatment. The findings of justice come to be pluralistic, realistic, and circumstantial, but on proportionality principle about the leeway of policy measures on different treatment. Aristocrats, perfectionists, and meritocrats would rely dominantly on this concept of equality and may be seen adapted in the kind of value argument from Dworkin (2013). A Case Review on the Equality Concern Let me brief on the case of equality controversy arising from the context of WTO measure. A preferential treatment for the underdeveloped countries in terms of tariff was deemed a kind of substantial justice or positive liberty in the initiative of UNCTAD around 1970’s. The rules and principles of WTO embedded a non-discrimination and liberalization 46 of trade, which governs the international trade regime. Hence the member states are owed to respect the fundamental principle which crystallized into the MFNT and National Treatment as provided within the scope of multilateral trade agreements. These principles ensure, for example, that the member states are required to levy a same rate of tariffs if the goods are of “identical product.” Hence, the concept of Aristotle, “treat the like case as like” was employed in the end of acquiring an equal justice. The concept of proportional equality also is assured that WTO, through its policy vehicle, monitors and controls the nation’s trade policy in advance, and provides a legal stability and predictability in some of hierarchy and governance structure. A numerical concept of equality also was incorporated by instituting a political consensus system generally on equal vote concerning the issues and agenda of WTO. The threat to equality, then, would be obvious that the preferential treatment on tariffs violates the equality because of its nondiscriminatory imposition. Country A would be prejudiced about a different rate of tariff while Country B may benefit from such preferential treatment. Country C has to keep on her promise, say, a tariff concession, often effected in advance and as general to the whole of member states, toward or with Country A. However, a preferred status from the lower rate of tariff for Country B operates yielding an unfair outcome to decrease the expected share which should be entertained by A. A relational concept of equality would be obstructed, and obviates the requirement of MFNT. The factors in this contradiction is notorious involving a popular contention between the underdeveloped group and developed countries. This dilemma also relates with the concept of positive liberty and substantial justice. We perhaps may share a same concern and ways of approach in the ontological argument about the first principle of justice and distributive one as found in Rawls. His conclusion to legitimate a justification of international aids or grants would hint on an attribute of contention underlying this dilemma. If we apply the value approach from Dworkin, the value could be endorsed in some cases, but may be rejected in other context. For example, the controversy about any due extent of legal protection covering the intellectual property among the two groups are notable that the value to guide a shape of legal dealings about the extent of protection can still be arguable on its merits. Then the general concept of equality now turns on a specific nature that a morality aspect of equality, often endeavored on the laissez faire concept of equal opportunity, would be recast involving factors, as said above, actions, persons, social institutions, and circumstances and so. The positive liberty, in some stronger ethos, rose as we see in the enabling provisions, that justifies an exemption of WTO obligations based on the statutory causes. The provision of General Exception would also indemnify the duties and obligations prescribed in the trade treaty. Here also was involved a political commission of UNCTAD, whose role is expected to support the underdeveloped economies. However, the attempt to institute a preferential system of tariffs on behalf of the underdeveloped countries initially failed to find a space in chapters of GATT. The way to recourse so as to pillory these inequalities could only be practicable through resolving the issue politically. A political nature of provision to deal with the exemption of duties and obligations is the Waiver clause, which can be granted by the weightier majority vote. This course actually was followed in the course of instituting the system, what we call GSP. Some Cases on the Distributive Justice 47 Please let me outline several issues entailing some of dilemma in our intuition of justice or equality, which I have considered to reflect our realities in the contemporary society (West, C., 1989). First, the UN framework is interesting to operate, in major, within two dimensions between the General Assembly and Security Council. The former organ accommodates all member states as their constituent in dealing with the organizational responsibility. They, however, have no realistic power to decide on a coercive action or remedy unlike the National Congress. The UN Security Council would be a unique organ to impose a compulsory measure or sanction where we also have two types of member states between “permanent and non-permanent.” The permanent members of UN Security council are comprised of five major powers, and non-permanent ones would range at ten. The latter serves a two years term, and the permanent members have the power to veto where one dissent may null any possibilities of coercive measure for the international justice and against intolerable challenges. Given the equal right of state to her sovereignty in the international community, the non-member state may complain about their status, particularly if the state is economically powerful or maintains on international bearing as the kind of lead or influence. Second, the global economy, in this contemporary framework, requires the states to be interdependent among another, and virtually could not survive if in shutdown from the international trade regime. This leads to such a high number of WTO memberships, about over 150, and recently allows us to witness the entrance of Russia and China. The advent of this behemoth was achieved in 1995 through the valiant efforts of international policy makers and on extensive negotiation of so long a seven years, from what we call Uruguay Round. The scope of jurisdiction expanded and many intricacies to catalyze their public role and function were instituted. For its foundational vision, almost all of significant global states were incorporated that the component and attribute of member states would be highly incongruent. Some states may be unable to the dire needs of people, and the national system of economy may take a different path as we find in the Communist case. In this background, the contention in basic ways of approach is notable, what we often call the North and South issue. The southern states, located in the southern part of hemisphere, are populated by low income earners, hence, massively underdeveloped countries. That is posed as opposite for the northern states. They are nevertheless as tuned, in tons of proposition, with the liberalization ethos and framework, which WTO envisages as its ideals and coincides with the developmentalist claim on the “level playing field.”In the counter thesis, the less capable states may raise their position in favor of the more concretized concept of substantive equality. Third, the admission policy of public universities are expected to administer fairly based on the quality and his academic achievement. That is required given its nature of organization which would not be compared to the private universities. In some cases, we bubble on a gossip about lots of donation, esoteric or other exterior element involving the children of famous politicians or superrich, which allegedly factors an admission decision of the prestigious private universities. However, that is just the case for pass time. In the context of public universities, it could be disputed as a matter of law, what we are familiar with in the label of affirmative action. The context gives us a useful point when we think about the nature and essence of equality and social justice. It exposes a scope of elements in contention which are often raised as a focal point to deliberate. To say, the simple or complex equality, 48 equality for welfare, choice and responsibility, equality of result, equality of resources and functioning, and so on, which many scholars visited to consider. Principles of Equality, Resolution and Points of Thought Let us consider the first case through the thoughts. The libertarianism has a repercussion to claim its primate value from the right to original freedom, being largely critical about the social right and redistribution policy (SEP, 2013). The state entity is often considered to enjoy the kind of similar aspect on an individual, hence, inviolable nature of selfdom and right to equal treatment in the international norms. We hardly find whatsoever reason to any privileged status, in principle, for the class of nations. A realistic lesson and history may influence the shape and work role within the UN enabling the concept that even a political issue is not to be complacent with the simple equality (Jeffreys-Jones, R., 2013;West, C., 1989). The concept of complex equality may be of use to explain this exposure if the permanent members are viewed to possess the power of policing the international community. A historical contingency upon the bitter World War II also factored to create this power structure, so that the utilitarian concept of equality would less be pertinent to arrive at persuasive reasoning. That is because the theory presupposes an equal share in tenet to maximize the happiness of constituents. Japan and Germany, for example, however, would no longer be saturated given the elapse of long decades and their rise or emerging impression nowadays. The choice and responsibility argument may enlighten a ground for this contemporary structure. Since two nations voluntarily assumed to wage the war and incurred a breach of peace, they should be responsible to be excluded from the sensitive foundation of world politics. From the camp on equality of resources, the “veil of ignorance” works importantly to explain the distributive justice as in Rawls, so that the difference principle may find its dimension on justice (SEP, 2013). They are, therefore, innocent from an unjust consequence from the circumstances beyond his or her control. They are responsible, however, to the consequence grounded on his decision or action. The tenet came rather applied in the case of Dworkin or Sen where the former shed a more emphasis on “ambition- sensitive” as a prelude to the Sen’s “equality of functioning” (2013). Both stressed on a human element and the life conditions more emphatically than the resources or economic elements. In this sense, we can note an “endowment-insensitive” plane that Dworkin has played to enable an equal intelligence, choice, decision, and value. He, then, would be more callous about the materialistic anonymity or capitalistic logic embedded on the autonomous or inhumane dynamism. His illustration, “hypothetical auction,” also implies his undertaking about the importance of human strands, which perhaps would be tuned most vividly with the choice of each individual. This way of thinking is less helpful in the first case given the realistic road of international politics would see the materialistic elements, such as the extent of nuclear capabilities and the national strengths dominantly from a materialistic quality on the basis (West, C., 1989). However, the creative economy and web-based business or industry, now in public attention, could be discussed intimately on his version of justice. Apple may have no manufacturing base or large facilities of factory. It earned a tremendous amount of dollars simply with some of high tech web network, which could well surprises the global public about its aggregate of corporation value in the stock market. We also occasioned, in the newspaper, a success story of information business, the function of which is distinctive from the traditional ways of business. Even the scholarly sector of business, say, contribution of 49 article to the journals, e-books and articles, and the mode of education and so, turns on the internet-based interplay. The equality of functioning, as Sen focused, needs to be adjusted by incorporating a technological advancement. For example, unincorporated limited liability entities (ULLC) are now to be a dominant form of internet-based business, which provokes our thought about the ethics, fiduciary duties of officers and directors, and possible misuse of business form as well as due regulation. What is an endowment in this case, in the sense of Dworkin, would perhaps be gotten in a different strand like the Apple’s case. The equality of resources concept can yield a very instant conclusion to support the current standard of WTO practices, and that would also be complemented with Rawls and Sen (SEP, 2103). How to boost the underdeveloped economies is a serious concern that we need to ponder through the delivery of trade justice in the international community. They may well be viewed to manage on the veil of ignorance and within the circumstances beyond their control. For example, they plainly would be frustrated with the level of high protection given the current standing of national science and the needs to draw any requisite knowledge or technology for their developmental paradigm. We perhaps would find no ways to accuse them of any control or choice on their behalf. The context also corroborates with the “equality of welfare,” though in some variations toward any “maximization of welfare” in the WTO commitment. A theme of WTO would likely be on the tons of welfare advocacies often available from the politicians. This attribute contributes to a special treatment of underdeveloped countries by exempting them from an instant institution and implementation of the western standard of legal protection for the intellectual property rights. They may be privileged by obtaining a legal counsel under the aid of WTO administration bureau and institutionally from the special proceeding requirements. This is because they are less competent to legally claim their interests and rights by formal proceedings. This status is also pertinent to the ambition-sensitive or functioning version from Dworkin and Sen (2013). In this aspect, the privileged group of states would be ambitious to play within the WTO system despite a less endowment and vulnerable capacities in disparity with their developed peers. That may be remedied from many provisions and practices instituted to procure the substantive justice and equality. I suppose that the third case has a distinctive element as notable against other two, say, the past wrong. The affirmative action designed and practiced in the US involves the concern and policy strand to cure the past wrong. Other justice theories most always trigger a progressive and future looking moral argument as in the equality of resources and functioning, ambition-sensitive equality as well as the equality of welfare. It poses, therefore, challenges about the equality and responsibility, perhaps pluralism and democracy or merits based approach. The affirmative action may serve a pluralism or democracy leading to the social congruence, but may damage some of merit based approaches often considered pivotal in the public education. That may relate with the equality of welfare in a distant picture, directly in some extent involving the affirmative action of public bidding, and rather constructively in the school admission policy cases. However, the countervailing argument based on the merit or quality of students is also strong. For example, they argue that a female would be assessed inferior to the male students in view of the learning and intellectual capabilities. Their message cast a suspicion of why only the black students are preferred in the admission decision. Part of countering argument may rely on the theme of curing the past wrong. It perhaps requires, however, undertaking a long journey to persuade from the different principle and veil of ignorance. We may be reluctant to endorse the factors beyond an 50 applicant control, and our usual criticism on the “brute-luck egalitarianism” can find a ground (2013). This generally pushed the court back from the generous stance by wavering on the case-by-case basis concerning its constitutionality. Reference Jeffreys-Jones, R. (2013). In Spies We Trust: The Story of Western Intelligence, New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Equality (2013). Retrieved from http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/equality/. West, C. (1989). The American Evasion of Philosophy: A Genealogy of Pragmatism (Wisconsin Project on American Writers). Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin Press. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/equality/ 51 X. On the Equity An Outskirt Highway and the Equity of Traffic Fare Seoul is the capital city in Korea, and furnished an outskirt highway to round travel the city. The city officer recently announced that toll booths for the fare to use would be installed. In other words, use of highway now turns to be managed of the paid basis from free of charge system. The public now critically assess the nature of policy shift in square points of contention. One expert, Yong-hoon Park, who serves the Traffic Culture and National Campaign (TCNC), commented, it would be inextricable to change the system. In earlier years, the free of charge system would be effective and mutually beneficial. That is because a number of toll booths require an extended budgetary burden to install at all the lamp entrance places. In this case, the equity interest would not be well served, but the feasibility and overall value on the public benefit would be traded off (Laureaute Education Inc., 2013; Cooper, T.L, 2012). It is, as we know, highly related with the regional transportation demands, and the situation changed rapidly to aggravate toward an intolerable inequity among the region. That is caused by the increase of use exploiting a free of charge system. Other challenge also thrills the policy makers that some specific cuts of entire highway is conspicuously congested with many cars, trucks and buses. This incurs the traffic flows in the problematic cut of area would be baffled at lower speed by two times. Then the Seoul citizens, who would be a major clientele in this issue, can ask, “Why was the change not implemented initially, but after ten years on the free of charge system?” The answer is that the fare collection management has been upgraded recently at the aid of technological provision. This enabled to lower an installation expense, and could be afforded an equal distribution of public service. One problem is still unresolved that the identification system of auto license number has not been 100 percent–proven quality. Therefore, the follow-up measure and efforts are necessary to verify the capacity of current identification instruments. Other chores to trouble a perfect implementation of new system would be the post-travel collection attached on the HIGHPASS exception. In this case, the collection rate is less, so that the course of collection management needs to be tightened and strictly enforced. In terms of equity, the north and south division seems to incur a graver disparity. The above scenario only would pertain to the south division which the Korean Road and Highway Management (KRHM) is responsible for. As in cases, the equity in this Division may be improved. However, the north division, unlike the south, was launched in the responsibility of private enterprises, and the fare to travel has already doubled to the southern case. How do we evaluate this context of inequality between the north and south. The south division, as antedated to the North, was not privatized. However, due to the fiscal cliff, the north division took a different approach to increase the fare at 2.6 times higher. This disparity in the use of public service yields disgruntled clients and highly wavers the residents as depending on the financial problem. If the government is financially affordable, it could purchase the privatized section of highway, the north division. Then the problem may be lessened, but still pounding is it that it could not settle on the challenge of beneficiary’s rule. For the non-users, the inequity would be obvious about why the government appropriated the tax only for the class of highway users. Under the current status of issue, a most plausible alternative is that KRHM purchases the privatized north, but with some countervailing option 52 to complement a fiscal deficit. The precedent could say some that Korail once has the same fiscal dilemma, but that they could be aided by taking over the management of Inchon Airport Rails. The policy wisdom can solve to lower the fare of north (2013). One other issue in terms of equity and social justice is that some highways had been replete of their basis of collection since the construction and maintenance expense was already recovered. They, nonetheless, continue to collect the fare. This problem also leads to think about the inequity among a various nature of clients. Some may reside in the area where the highways have a long history. Others may live to be adjacent with the newly built highway cut or section. This inequity, in nature, could hardly be addressed that the citizens of Inchon have no way to share tolerating. Some policy discretion could diversify the operation by building an underground road on the free of charge system. It can diminish an excessive use on the on-land highway which is a culprit of squeezing traffic congestion. A mere delivery of policy for the free of charge reform could not cure effectively the overall dissatisfaction of Inchon clients. Any imposing factor to the traffic users would be from the congestion more than a little higher fare to travel. In any case, this section in the coverage from Seoul through Incheon would bear the same way of solution that the management responsibility should be clarified and transferred to Inchon city (2012). Between the Two types of Medical Service One other public issue to be related with the equity concern in Korea has been discussed in the National Assembly. Eon-ju Lee, a congress woman from The Public Health Committee in NA, raised an issue about the inequity of the National Health Insurance between the Western mode hospitals and Eastern Methodist clinics. Korea has two types of health service which is official. That differs from the US and other western states. Probably, this dual system, which is sustained from the public education, tax and public insurance program, and others, would often be practiced within the Oriental states on earth. Mrs. Lee cast her critical viewpoint, “the public health insurance needs to be designed on the basis of medicare demand, scientific basis of health service, as coupled with the patient’s financial burden. Any most important standard to weigh the various factors of policy issue would be an equity. The Eastern Methodist health service now achieved an international standard of health science, and the national demand has increased steadily. The public education to breed its professionals often had been included in many universities along with the western mode medical college. Nonetheless, it is unreasonable to discriminate the types of health service in terms of the national health insurance program. Mrs. Lee illustrated the statistical data by pointing to some grossly limited ambit of national insurance policy. In Dec. 2009, the Eastern Methodist physical treatment was incorporated as the policy item of NHIP. Afterwards in the next four years, it turned to be a stalemate without any addition of policy item. This stalemate would be get worse if the initial scope was found to be limited about three sub-strands of policy item, not all of scope we often denote with the meaning of “physical therapy” The total amount of subsidies from the government is as less as 24.4 million dollars in 2011, and 21.7 million dollars in 2010. This passive nature of number shows the government has been unresponsive to the emerging demand of nationals for this type of health care. According to the statistic bureau of government, the satisfaction rate of nationals from this type ranges at 55.9%, which indicates some higher than the western type. Given this, she saw no reason if the scope of physical 53 therapy was limited in the insurance purpose, which would be contrary with a comprehensive recognition for its counterpart. This flaw of system and an unequal treatment without the proper ground about classification would bring a discriminatory effect on the share of patrons within the health service. It also exhibits the harms to make a chilling effect against its universalization. The expansion of insurance scheme is now greatly demanded, according to her view, to increase the public incorporation of Eastern Methodist as well as equity among the different taste of nationals. Some Reflections on the Equity A promise of equity often is desired to restore the fundamental justice, hence, possesses a quality in subtle difference from the equality (2013). Most plainly, the common law system has two types of court division between the Court of Chancellor and ordinary court. The ordinary courts are responsible to administer a technical issue of law and often involve dealing with the issue as a matter of law. The whole concept of justice often can be graced from the Court of Chancellor as a matter of equity. The tradition of legal institution rooted in the equity court also could be found in the contemporary US laws, such as the specific performance, injunctive relief and so. The equity concept often requires a grand scale of wisdom, whose nature can be more salient in the public administration than in the administration of justice. For example, it appeals to the nature of humanity and social justice so that the jumble of difficult legal theories may be avoided. While the public administrators need to understand the law, the policy measure and its shaping would be creative to respond with the political and social challenges. This attribute can be seen as distinctive from the nature of judicial role. Across the two cases imposed now in Korea, the clients of public service and other parties involved would be impacted to incur a possible loss from the inequity. The nature of issues was posited in the economic justice and equal access to the provision of public service. As we see in the doctrine of commercial speech concerning the first amendment issue, the issue would be dealt less serious when we approach in the shoes of judicial business. Unlike the library case of disabled, it does not entail any intrinsic of humans. Then the library case would be more amenable to the logic and metaphor in equality as we often encounter in the case laws (Kranich, N., 2007). The highway fare and different treatment of two types of health services, on the other hand, may be looked into from the road of equity quest. There would be a lesser of accurate rules and any common law justice, rather the public administrators can tackle the issue vastly from his professional inner mind process, which would be evaluative, analytical, politically and economically sensible, and socially agreeable, and also comprehensive beyond a specific rule of law (Cooper, T.L, 2012). Through the Chevron, the court developed this aspect notably in the label of “judicial deference” about the administrative actions. An Equity Issue in Inchon Nam-Gu and Its Impact Inchon Nam-Gu is the prescient that functions on the independent statute ground and as a local government. Mr. Park served as a major of city, who is responsible as an ultimate decision maker about the permit and license to construct. He recently revoked a 54 construction permit around the time when the Muslim temple was virtually completed and foresaw to lay a cornerstone. As the completion embarked and it had been progressed under the construction permit, this sudden and unforeseeable drastic measure surprised the public. The people suspect if the measure is arbitrary and abusive as well as in violation of the universal rights, such as free exercise of and equality among different religions (Laureate Education Inc., 2013). The Inchon Nam-Gu Branch of Civil Association claimed a full disclosure of administrative dealings including a background, motives and reason to reach the revocation conclusion. According to the source of branch, “the decision was rendered that one section of parking lot was not furnished as legally required to meet the permit change from the educational to the religious facilities.” However, the decision was impermissibly drastic and in contradiction of equity or common concept of justice, which forecloses any cure and correction. Nam-Gu, in the progress of construction, has affirmed the change of design and purpose of construction, which incurs a problem of public distrust concerning the city administration. This concept has been affirmed by the court and in theory of administration law in Korea that the government is precluded from the action, decision, or disposition as contrary to the established trust from those of past dealings. A public excuse announced by Nam-Gu elicited that the terminal measure of this kind often is purported to sanction or invoked in the exercise of disciplinary authority. This case has gone in the same context. The Branch raised its tone of criticism that the public administration has to keep a neutral and balanced concept of diverse interest groups and public. It is required as a matter of administrative ethics and to ensure a responsible administration (Cooper, T.L., 2012). Absent this prudence in the score of public issues and resolution, it is, as a matter of course, deemed illegitimate, usurped of power, unethical and irresponsible, as well as arbitrary against the equity and justice (Laureate Education Inc., 2013; Kranich, N. , 2007; SEP Economics and Economic Justice, 2013). The Branch also elucidated that the Christian society petitioned with 50,000 signatures containing their resentment and opposition against the construction. This may work as a pressure and may present an implied and hostile circumstance leading ineluctably to reach this decision. Of course, the suspicion could well be based if this inequitable decision was to avoid a possible backlash from the Christian society. A political compromise in the coming election with a major religious group and as discriminatory of the minor one would factor this prejudice as well as the odd administrative decision. The Branch also heralded that the present decision would hardly be sustained. This is evidenced that the suit already was brought to the courtroom and the boycott of Asian Games is being considered seriously in reaction. It expressed gravely that the present decision would undermine a national honor in the international community in the face of Asian Games. Against the sprit and expectations from the Games, it may provoke a distrust or antipathy among the Asian countries. Finally, the Branch urged a reconsideration of this issue to restore the equity and free exercise of religion. An Equal treatment between the different religious group is expressly ordained in Korean constitution, and history lets us to make sacred and sensitive to correct. In any case, a narrow focus on one sphere only often may invite a contention, turfs, or public criticism. This means that the neglect on any one essence would pay a due price as we notice in many of public controversies. The case above introduced can be seen well in this context. Other point to merit our concern would be autonomous and self-serving tendencies of the large and bureaucratic structures. As Appleby suggests, when functioning properly the hierarchy is, the structure of responsibility would tell its axiomatic process of justice and equity (2012). That could, however, encounter a high chance of variance from 55 the challenges, the nature of complicacies in the agenda and issues, political wind, personal interests, and particularly moral mazes or callous routines. Other useful dualism in approaching an equity or ethical decision making would cover the deontological (duty- oriented) and teleological (consequentialist) dimension in philosophy, and could facilitate the difficult technical strands or requirements in more principled resolution. This way of thinking also serves much to address the challenge of equity issue in the workplace (2013; 2007). An ethics issue involved in this case is serious to impact on the Korean people and Nam-Gu officials as briefed above. As the officer of local government is paid in wage as less than the private employees, their sense of honor and personal conviction as a fiduciary trustee are any principal factor to pull their vigor of service. His or her self-esteem would be affected to discourage their followership. They suspect if the decision could comport with societal expectations of the nation (2012). The Asian Games will be some Korean favorite in the process of years on its preparation, public sharing of progress, occurrence of events, and through the aftermath in economic benefit to the locale and international prestige conducive to the success. They could even be frustrated from the neighbor’s criticism and ill ways of dealing to invite an international controversy. The leadership of mayor also can be derogated by the suspicious and disloyal attitude of officers. The local autonomy and its constitutional subscription in chapter had long been debated since the nation is small in the scale and function and on a congruent basis in view of ethnicity and national history. The opposing views perceived that the restructuring of national administration in a dual dimension would unnecessarily burden the national budget and may operate as contrary to a fiscal soundness. These views had been held throughout the decades of militaristic government in 1970’s and 1980’s, but the democratic passion of nation has, in a tough assumption, endorsed it as one of constitutional mandate in the late 1980’s. This foundation may well be vitiated at this incident in the mind of officers and Korean people in general that the mayor lost a strategically paramount side of his policy decision. The Muslim people, who resided in Korea also has a worse impression from this unanticipated overhauling of initial undertaking. As the right to free exercise of religion is universal in tenet and human rights framework, their disappointment would never be surprising. They consider gravely the contradiction of decision to the requirement of ethics that the responsible administration has to respect. In the substantive aspect of issue, it would be dubious if such minor point of violation could result in such serious consequence, say, a revocation of license continued in effect over the years. Hence the proportionality principle could be weighed in the negative force against the decision of mayor. Recommendations, Decision Making Model and Factors In applying the decision making model to the equity issue, I found it finer to rely on the four planes of deliberation model as reflected below (2012). (A) The conscious delimitation of commitment to an employing organization and the cultivation of identities that transcend its boundaries. A propensity and perception of mayor could be questioned to have a bias and narrowly focused to being misled by himself. He is an elected official who would calculate and plot on the public response and impact on the election. In this aspect, the decision can be compromised or even bribed with the majority religious group. He seems quite to be 56 dismantled to apprehend the nature and quality of issue. It seriously transgresses the normal standard of equity and justice element to prejudice the Muslim minority (2007). The conscious delimitation of commitment to en employing organization would be failed in coming into any reality and practical force to determine the issue. He seems to be overwhelmed by his personal interest of re-election. As a professional, he also seems to craft his own ways to cultivate the ethical identities, and neither on any continued practice with the design approach in shaping an ethical decision. Given a respect of this advice, the chances to render this type of ill decision would be inconceivable. (B) Legal and institutional protection for individual rights and conscience The local government operates under the constitutional structure and its mandate is a guide in hierarchy to be faithfully honored. It is also an ultimate factor often recommended to respect in face with the difficult and multifaceted ethical dilemma. The mayor’s decision seems to contravene this requirement so that it harms the equity and justice well assumed to be due for the Muslim minority. His personality can also be questioned if to cling to the reelection possibilities by attracting the majority voters, in this case, the Christian group in Nam-Gu. It obstructs a conscience often seen essential to be required of responsible administrators as a public fiduciary. Overcoming the conflict of interest might be pressing leading to the impermissible emphasis on a minor requirement of laws and regulation as well as the breach of principles (C) An ethic of awareness and cultivation of principled thinking. The mayor, as a responsible administrator, has to practice an ethic of awareness which cover a scope of elements, i.e., adequate knowledge, exposure to the general ways of approach and specifics in issues, organizational structure and culture, as well as societal expectations. Being more aware of the nature of issue and standing points of controversy, more ethical and practically efficient policy decision can be shaped and implemented. The issue, in this case, includes a sensitive policy area about the religion of minority in Korea, and also entails an aspect of diplomacy as well as the universal notion of human rights. The mayor should have to comprehend an enhanced level of the Korean culture in this light. Korea is a nation of international esteem due to its public virtue and culture. The selection as a host country of Asian Games plainly vindicates our international status in this respect. He failed to apprehend this aspect to disappoint the heat and passion of Asian countries from the commitment and trust by selling his responsibility to his political transaction or personal interest. As mentioned above, if he accepted the lesson and practiced a cultivation of principled thinking over the course of his professional career, the ways of dealings and outcome would develop in other ways. Recommendations and Factors in Implementation A solution to facilitate the correction of perceived evils in his final rendering of decision seems straightforward, say, revoking the decision of revocation of license and endorsing a completion of construction on the pertinent statutory basis, but upon a condition to fix the flaws of parking lot requirement. As the Christian people are a mass of their constituents, their support seems pivotal to administer a city politics and governance. Hence, the public forum could be planned to explain the course of development concerning the issue and obtain their recognition of legitimacy and propriety about the cure. 57 The factors operating in a contrary or facilitating influence may be explored if to pertain to the individual attributes, organizational structure and culture, as well as social expectations. The individual attributes of city mayor can factor in facilitating the cure and proper remedy to the public condemnation. The city mayor may be stubborn on his decision, and can think if he may bent to the public pressure (2012). However, the civil monitor group worked effectively to enable a full disclosure of the administrative process. The high chances would be that it also can facilitate the administrative cure to restore an equity value. Over the decades, particularly in the recent trend, the head of local government often has been arrogant and stresses the local autonomy in neglect of the national needs in uniformity. The governor of Kyung Nam Province showed a determined attitude against the call of National Assembly to make an appearance in the investigatory session. He actually went his own way to shut down a public project for the aged people in the claims about the fiscal deficit of local government. His testimony was deemed precious, but his logic and understanding was fairly entrenched that the any subpoena of NA would be repugnant to the separation of powers principle. He eventually sustained himself his views and NA took no action to escort him in the purpose to realize his presence in the session. This implies that the heads and directors of local government entertain a greater conviction as an elected official leading to a tension between the central and local governments. The social expectations in this case, however, come higher than other cases so that more chances would lie to favor the possibility of cure. In terms of organizational structure, the mayor is placed at the center of power to remedy his vulnerable action. He would be directly responsible to cure the revocation decision, but the practices often do not submit to that way of dealings. The local government often cherishes the stability of decision that most cases to be remedied would process in the judicial proceedings. As the nature of issue is highly sensitizing and touches on the core of Korean concerns, say, the international games and human rights, the organizational structure and culture may possess the quality of dual side of coins in view of limiting or facilitating my recommendation. Reflections As we learnt, we expect the public administrators would be ethicists to make a legally valid, effective and efficient decision to maximize its utility and happiness of organizational members and constituents. Their decision, hence, could be examined in the organizational strategy and planning to have an essential bearing with the imagery of organizational development specialists (2012). The case briefed above entails a miscalculation of policy sequence and actually created the gash that now, amid the public reaction as acid, hardly avoids the alternative to squelch on its basis. While the public administrator would be a juggler managing a multitude of competing obligations and interests, the case actually revealed a vicious aspect of unethical contemplation involving the political interest of mayor himself. Often we believe, as Michener commented, that he or she, as a responsible administrator, needs to pay a due respect to the real moral problems in the abstract where character is formed, hence, they may not be fragile to be a miscreant of policies and specific decisions of challenging nature (2012). This would require, over the course of professional development, of ethical identity beyond their title and status, and can appropriate the mechanism to reach the ethical decision as suggested by Cooper (2012). Four levels would foreground the process to deliberate on behalf of responsible administrators, what we staged in the inner mind process on evaluation or assessment. They would cover the expressive level, level of moral rules, ethical level and post ethical level. The level corresponds in dimension with the process espoused in the Cooper’s design 58 approach including the identification of issue, available options of ethical decision, and probable consequences, and so. The public administration often involves some share of leeway in the spectrum of public values and ethics as leading, lesser in extent, to any ineluctable conclusion. We often rather are susceptible of ample choices to deal, and often reach more like an aesthetic logic or gestalt in the end purpose to attract the citizenry (2012). The public administrators are postulated well in its practical role to respect the obligations to the citizenry and the organization established to serve the citizenry. The public employees would favor to develop a professional career and buy in, in many probabilities, the compensation in the monetary form or promotion, which their conduct or activities may lead to. They nonetheless can see a vignette well-rounded life outside the work. This well vindicates the thesis about the spectrum from the individual attributes through societal expectations. That often, as a tenet in the basics, coheres, and should do, but the issues or agenda may be complicated in a contradictory demand or in conflict of interests. As the policy issues, in this diverse society, are staged amok over the factors and interest groups, the admonition from Ralph Kilmann's to avoid “quick fixes” would help and they could base their dealings on the more practical and comprehensive context (2012). That said, it would project over the internal and external controls as general approaches and specific techniques. The responsible administrators would also be attached with a deep awareness and professional attitude to interplay with the individual attributes, organizational structure, organizational culture, and societal expectations. For example, we would know ourselves that an inherent tension exists between the individuals and the organizations where they are employed. On this point, we need to take an in-depth reflection about the possibility of individual ethical autonomy in the organizations. Then we may explore the useful suggestion about four elements so as to be responsible and in the ambit to produce a working ethics and interactive leadership; “(1) the conscious delimitation of commitment to an employing organization and the cultivation of identities that transcend its boundaries, (2) legal and institutional protection for individual rights and conscience, (3) an ethic of awareness, and (4) the cultivation of principled thinking” (2012). Reference Cooper, T.L. (2012). The Responsible Administrator, San Francisco. CA: Josey-Bass. Kranich, N. (2007). Equality and equity of access: What's the difference? Retrieved July 10, 2008 from the American Library Association Web site: http://www.ala.org/offices/oif/iftoolkits/toolkitrelatedlinks/equalityequity. doi: 388396 Laureate Education Inc., (2013). Ethics and Social Justice "Equality and Equity: Applications" with Amanda Baker (approximately 6 minutes) Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Economics and Economic Justice http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2008/entries/economic-justice/ http://www.ala.org/offices/oif/iftoolkits/toolkitrelatedlinks/equalityequity http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2008/entries/economic-justice/ 59 XI. On the Liberty The Disabled in South Korea The disabled in Korea perhaps like to ride on the public bus to go somewhere they wish to reach. The subway was not well exploited to suffice the details of specific destination. The public bus was most catalyzed to serve the travel needs of public in Korea, however, we often cannot find the disabled on the bus. The distance from a road to the bottom of bus normally is 98 centimeters (Kee-ryong, K, 2002; Graff, J., 1985). Even for the normal people on the inconvenient knees, riding onto the bus could be challenging. This would certainly exacerbate on the case of disabled. For the manufacturers in Korea, the disabled has long since not been assumed as the scope of passenger. They are treated in discrimination as same like the aged, pregnant woman, children, and the patient to suffer on his legs and knees. The developed countries, i.e., Japan, US and France, have earlier lowered the gap in 30 centimeters, and also provided an equipment to support the users of wheel chair (2002; 1985). Striking is it that Daewoo, a Korean auto manufacturing corporation, already produced this special bus in system, but its purchase has been made on the special order only to meet an occasion. For the improvement of environment, the public bus was mandated to use LNG. The road and traffic sign was neatly reformed to enhance the international events. However, the concerned people regret to find no policy or public support to provide for the disabled. A higher gap about 98 centimeters now frustrate the types of disabled which even include a brain damaged and deaf faced with the insufficient public signs. Particularly, the scene of hurried bus departure to leave the blind drastically often disappoints us. They would have no way but to ride the wheel chair lift which is highly vulnerable to risk his life. Their only way to reach his destination, however, is to use the subway loosely scattered and to undertake a long way to walk. The disabled has been described as a cursed creature in Greek myths. They are treated incompetent to labor and forced to be subject to a public charity or benevolence. They have to hang on his tough life through a deceased in time (1985). The Universal Declaration of Human Rights incorporated their status as a national, who became safeguarded from an infringement on his or her bodily autonomy or freedom. The Weimar constitution enacted in Germany in 1919 could pioneer a state commitment about the social welfare and provision of public program for the disabled. The MB administration of Korea in the past five years had been reluctant to expand the social welfare program and the ethos or passion of society often perceived the disabled as poor and as merely the class of social benevolence (Kee-ryong, K., 2002). Their status may not be elevated to a certain of right or personal interest so as to be protected by law. A previous point of financial burden or declaratory status of constitutional prescription also is not an exception for Korea. Nonetheless, it would be problematic if the Korean constitution lacks an express language to cover them in the ambit of constitutional policy (2002). This leads us to any contrast with the ways of Bonn constitution, which incorporated the class of disabled as one factor if to centralize on the pursuit of social justice. As the constitution is a ground law and often to be referred as a basic morality guideline of nation, this lacking pushed back the critically deprived class of people, namely disabled. A Free Mobility of Disabled and its Infringement 60 A free mobility of disabled in Korean society would be concerned of positive liberty since it does not require the absence of coercion from external factors. An approach to this societal issue rather mandates a public commitment to increase the freedom of person to move and travel. It presumes a certain provision of public aids and would underlie the concept of social justice. Rawls intuition, a “veil of ignorance,” may echo that we are responsible to address that entrenched inequality and their challenge to freely move. How much extent of inconvenience and frustration in the personhood of disabled perhaps would be immeasurable for well persons to sense and apprehend. It would entail both issues on equality and liberty. In the traditional concept of negative liberty or lassies faire liberalism, the problem could well be blinded to let it as is (SEP: 2013). The concept of positive liberty or functional focus on the societal virtue may have some strength to ground any of public measure. Rawlsian concept of social justice would consider a scope of factors, personal talents or competence, resources or wealth as distributed in comport with the first principle, the kind of liberty capitalized to found the basis of modern society, and others. The policy makers are assumed, in the power and competence to find an avenue to realize the social justice, and shape the proper and most effective policy instrument to bridge the first principle and social justice. The group would generally be considered to have surfaced in a more extent of legitimacy and democratic representation from the beginning of 20 th century. They may be posed a challenge by the libertarian circle of orthodoxy on the property right and absolute freedom to resources. As we see, what basis would entitle the owner and user of resources, then, provokes a serious contention around the abusive social welfare program. However, I suppose that an aid to the disabled would often fit within their ambit since they lodge a highest emphasis on the liberty interest. An issue of disabled presented above entails the nature of positive liberty since it triggers the target group to be “liberalized to certain thing,” as not in meaning “the liberty from something.” However, the shape of issue may differ in a subtle context although the argument of positive liberty in ways of approach would look into the internal factors on a true self (2013). This often implies that the agent would exercise a moral process in deciding to act or omit to act. Nonetheless, the issue of disabled on free mobility touches on the basic operation of bodily liberty, and concerns an intrinsic mishap in the distribution of resources. He or she is innately paralyzed to be disabled from movement. Some of them may acquire his unfortunate state from the industrial accident or war sacrifice. Factors to be Considered The profile of issue then develops into a complex equality by not being submissive to any simple notion of equality. In view of liberty, they share a common ground, however, as to be physically depraved to something. Their function to make him or herself as a social ego would be infringed to get incongruent and his personal liberty was critically abridged. The enhanced concept of liberty now requires that the principle cannot serve the whole of requirement if to merely let them to free in the absence of any external coercion. An enjoyment of certain condition to the decent human standard is often envisaged by the policy makers and explains for some of prevailing understanding of liberty discourse in the contemporary society. A liberty discussion also can be made to require the whole of picture if the agent actually does certain things in certain ways? The triadic way of approach involving the agent, purpose and constraints proposed by Christman may direct to be sucked into the topology of liberty assessment (2013). A constraint would constitute the key factors in 61 concern, and the absence of any kind of constraint whatsoever on the realization of one's true self could be a critical test to the desired state. It would also be corroborated by the simple standard as Green and Bousanquet encapsulated, say, “the absence of all factors that could prevent the action x” (2013). The modern views also put an emphasis on the comparative assessment to arrive at the sound stream of societal justice on liberty. Hence, as commented below, the US ways to deal with the issue would illustrate a desired state in protection of the disabled to assist with their physical handicap. A comparative view with the US institution could help to comprehend how the liberty or personal freedom of disabled in Korea was discriminated. It is obvious that they actually cannot do certain things in certain ways. The context of Korea involving the liberty of disabled would clearly fail on this criterion. The US has also experienced a challenge and public debate split in contention concerning the extent of pubic provision and ways to boost them. A first statute to deal with the issue of disabled perhaps would be the Urban Mass Transportation Act (UMTA). This Act includes a policy goal that the aged and disabled have the right to equal access to the public transportation. It also prescribed the mandate of federal government to exert a special care in designing and planning the facilities and program of transportation service. In 1975, the Federal Aid Highway Act was enacted, which purported to mobilize a federal grant or subsidies to facilitate the public transportation for the disabled. A most ambitious and powerful scheme was arranged in the statute, what is called the Rehabilitation Act Section 504 in 1973. This act enabled a scope of public measure by incorporating the duties and obligations of private business. We may consider the standard of liberty for the disabled may be evaluated in variances, which led to the different extent of welfare provision for them. However, it is deplorable that a very basic liberty for the disabled was not succinctly addressed in Korea. The Concepts of Liberty and Politics The liberty would be an epistemologically cumbersome in any hard way of definition, but a ground to be explored and contended seriously in view of human intrinsic, social desirables, morality argument as well as the political terms of society. The liberty, therefore, would be on a due course of dynamism which exposes some incompatible interpretations of a single political ideal. For example, the relationship between the liberty and political ideals or desired frame of political process would not see an agreement between Constant, Humboldt, Spencer, Mill and Rousseau, Hegel, Marx or T.H Green (SEP, 2013). They would probably conceive a same extent of importance or value attached to the liberty, but their vision on the political dealings to address a modern sovereign state would diverge. Often the liberty would constitute one of ultimate goals that any respective political community envisages, pursues, or in the least not to taint the essences enshrined in the value of liberty. That would not be negated by both liberal and communist framework of politics. And even the regime of monarchy could share the idea of liberal subjects in the comprehension of value and in shaping a moral structure of society. Hobbes may be perceived in this purview about his proposition of social contract. He played under the assumption of authoritative monarch as a justification of politics, but ideated the ground of individual liberty to a safe condition, interests of life and limb as well as his or her property. It is an irony that the absolute power and sovereign can shake hands with the liberty concept. Rousseau’s collective will would dispose another errand to respond with the emerging thoughts on enlightenment and political 62 freedom. His idea made the rising class exuberant to entertain the liberty, and enabled to lay the positive concept of liberty by participation and activism to constitute the public will. It could be echoed in a similar fashion as coupled with a labor idealism that the communist society would be paramount in championing a human morality and liberation of self. An emancipation of the rising class in reliance with the social contract principle could be developed in any refined manner by Locke in his treatise on civil government. Based on his bureaucratic career, he derived many strands of public governance, and has been considered as to proffer a lee way of new understating from inference and interpretation (Murphy, A., 1998). His theory would be realistic in practical dialectics about the value of civil society and loyal government to process their responsibility. He recourses the public power from the social contact and an eclectic bridge between the civil power and sovereign. His idea, however, will culminate to favor the former so that a Regicide would be legitimate if to be exercised in the end of preventing an intolerable tyranny. His ways of governmental process could be seen in the separation of powers principle, which was to merit two or four independent attributes and to include the power to legislate and execute or power to consolidate on the different states. Perhaps in order over Hobbes, Rousseau and Locke, the primal concept of modern politics could be classed in view of the extent of authoritarianism, but three version would converge to the ideal of individual liberty (1998). The Positive and Negative Liberty When we deal with the concept of liberty, a most popular way of approach may be found in Berlin’s classification between the negative and positive liberty (SEP, 2013). The negative liberty, in essence, requires the absence of obstacle, barriers, or constraints, hence neither coercion nor intervention from the external strands, such as institution, society, notably government and other forces or influences. Its implication would bring a serious consequence in terms of political rightness and foregrounds in vast extent the basics to constitute the political community. It, in the application, led to the virtue of minimal state and has been most contributive to an economic dimension in developing the modern prosperity of liberal capitalism. The tenet would also still be maintained in virtually no diminution about the practical dominance of metaphor and logic in the contemporary global market. As the concept is presaged, the nature would be on prongs to be related with a biological freedom, natural law ideas, the kind of Darwinian ways of apprehension, and economy. For example, the pursuit of commercial interest would, in some light, be perceived as insurmountable and hardly curbed toward the impractical accumulation of wealth or capital. It can grow indefinitely to stage at some terminal self contradiction according to the communist moral perspective. It is plainly self-evident that the negative liberty would be most favorable that the enterprises would embrace. Recently, the public controversy aggravated at the news paper report of tax heaven. A plethora of Korean superrich allegedly exploited an opportunity of lower tax with the unauthorized export of their wealth and in a hidden way to evade the higher tax duties in Korea. As a host country, Haiti or Virgin Island under the British rule, manages on a benevolent national tax schedule and the banks or intermediaries in trust or estate could conspire to serve their unlawful purpose. A tax issue also created a public resentment in the Boston tea party, hence offered a revolutionary moment to liberalize the colonial merchants or land class. The nature of plutocracy in use to denote an early colonial state is generally undisputed and, in some respect, a more embedded interest and spirit to guide the structure of 1789 federal constitution. The wealth and negative liberty would be a close peer to fit as being championed inviolable (Murphy, A., 1998). Other area in an 63 important interplay with the negative liberty would concern the freedom of personhood. An unlawful seizure and arrest would be in a primary focus when we deal with the concept. A prevention of torture and privacy right to bear a personal appearance can also be exemplary at matter of negative liberty. The militaristic government in 1970’s of Korea enacted the statute to regulate the length of hair whose type would be often patronized by the entertainers and popular artists. The authority of government had ample ways to freeze the pedestrians on the street and imposed a fine or several days of detention in the police station merely on the basis of his hair look. A comrade court of former Soviet Union and the criminal justice system in Great Britain would serve the public goal by imposing a public requirement by the light penalty, but if the negative liberty may not be ensured in a perfect extent. This kind of institution can convivially disclose the operation of negative liberty which would be simple, basic, universal, and through the ultimate of personhood. Interesting is that the criminal justice system in Great Britain would rely on the lay judges, whom we often call a knight and which disposes a petit crime involving the breach of public peace. It is a greater way to exercise the state cause in interacting with the traditional virtue, but may possess the quality to impose the kind of positive liberty in an authoritarian understanding of public or personal moral as in the case of 1970’s Korea. The positive liberty, as hinted, rather deals with the whole of person beyond the nature or personal autonomy. It would be more friendly with the belief of Creationist version where the origin of human being is from the God. The nature and quality of human being would be cast to entertain a self-mastery and self-realization or self-determination, and they would intervene to define the concept of positive liberty (SEP, 2013). In this purview, the internal factors to hinder a liberty could come into play that a psychology or individual morality compounds the argument to shape any true nature of liberty or freedom. While the negative liberty would be framed “the liberty from something”, the positive one foregrounds a dynamism as “the liberty to something.” Hence, it is an applied level of understanding to interplay with the system and political process. As in the Rousseau’s introduction, the agent is required to participate in the political process to ensure their liberty interests. As Marx delineated, the human ought to understand a false consciousness and materialistic injustice or fallacy to betray the nature of humanity. They often call their army as a “liberation might,” as in the case of Korean war, and the liberation theology may develop a similar way of thought on the contemporary society. However, their failure to see the pluralistic nature of humanity, as entirely hallucinated with the materialistic dynamics, would be questioned. A tenet and ethos of positive liberty now offers the conceptual ground to the paternalist or moralist state intervention, and intermediates the third way of European politics, for example, as Giddens suggested (Crocker, L.H., 1980). A most opposing promise of western politics against the paternalistic intervention would be the neo-liberalism espoused by Reagan and Thatcher, which was founded to restructure the flaws and inefficiencies of 20 th welfare paradigm. The examples of positive liberty would be omnipresent in the contemporary affluent society. A Special District of public education may enable their students to function positively by providing a free IPad to support their study and leisure time. The temporary unemployed people in Korea would be afforded a small amount of pension money to reproduce their quality and standard on any job vacancies (Laureate Education Inc., 2003). National pensions for the teachers and government officers can be settled for the decent standard of living upon the retirement age. We can see “the liberty to something,” say, a decent living after some statutory age in this case. Around these cases, we can note that the simple absence of external coercion would not suffice to bring the positive liberty (Crocker, L.H., 1980). Hence, the concept of positive liberty envisages an assumption about the divided self, which 64 hypothesizes a higher self and lower one. On this concept, we note that our empirical desires would be complicated to enhance the dimension of liberty, but the positive liberty may be criticized to neglect on the external factors or political ultimatum which often is determinative about the mode of our existence and interplay. In other review, the critiques pointed to the similarities by illustrating the moral nature of proposition as we encounter in the ascetics, stoics and Buddist sages (SEP, 2103). An unilateral emphasis of the positive liberty can also be misleading because it involves a ‘retreat into an inner citadel’ — a soul or a purely noumenal self (2013). It is noteworthy, however, that some modern thinkers capitalize on the personal growth as the essence of liberty, which could compromise the above dualism and in the illustration of plants. The Political Liberalism and Contemporary Debate on the Liberty A sphere between the liberty concept and political liberalism actually would pose some practical challenges, but unfortunately hardly be reconciled in any expressive framework. This context can be adduced in the perception of Christman that the society is composed of supposedly heteronomous individuals (2013). Absent any definite answer, it would serve to “remain as is,” which would comport with one tactics of oriental wisdom from Paduk (Oriental chess). However, merely non-interference would say little that the virtue of liberty presumes an enjoyment of certain conditions. We consider a most influential promise over the wake of western democracy as neo-Roman (Quentin Skinner) or Republican liberalism (Philip Pettit). It can bridge the concept of liberty and democratic governance on the tradition and inviolable virtue long upheld in the statecraft. The concept of human rights, separation of powers principle, deliberative feature of democratic dynamism, and philanthropic assumption on a fiduciary duty, trust, frugality and others, would ground its ways of recognition and thinking (Laureate Education Inc., 2003). It also substantiates the institutions to practice democracy, and hence interplays with the liberty interest on an individual. A political liberalism in the contemporary context can also be contended as we note in the shutdown of federal government and national crisis of default. The kind of skepticism, “is it any subservient to the increase of positive liberty of Americans,” may be captured in the face of tremendous debt. However, we also question if it would be acceptable to paralyze the federal government which is responsible to ensure the basic liberty of American citizen. A defense and police service may be affected or the national park may fail to ensure the liberty toward a decent living and pleasant environment. The Republican liberalism or neo-Roman would proffer the institutions to regulate the permissible ways to interact with an individual. In this point of concern, the ways that the desire is formed would be emphatic and the government would be expected as neutral about the content of freedom as in the illustration of Muslim women by Christman (SEP, 2013). The same idea could be found in the time, place and manner regulation concerning the First Amendment right. This implies that the content- based regulation on expression, in comparison with the content neutral, would be deemed more culpable and constitutionally suspicious subject to more chances of condemnation. Under the philanthropic ambit of liberty discourse, however, the educational exposure or cultural environment may affect even empirical desires, hence, the content of freedom, and a higher level or course of moral judgment. In other words, the internal factors would be created from his or her personal learning and experiences according to the view of Christman. Other strand entrenched in the Republican liberalism lies in non-domination and the kind of ultimate belief embedded on the positive correlative between the domination, 65 arbitrary power and threat to the liberty (2013). Hence it would be a virtue on their conviction to implore on the partisan switch of political power on a regular basis and to filibuster against the prevailing power in the Congress. In their wellness and conviction, the constraints on the political branch are always greater to secure the liberty interest. In their vision and tradition, the kind of Berlin’s fear about an infringement on the negative or positive liberty, mutas mutandis, the Chrysippus' understanding of self-determination, may be structurally eradicated since his fear would be cultivated by the fact that the political power may be liberal only on a whim. We generally consider that there is no distinctive use of two terms in the lay world and even in the academic or historical context, which are between the liberty and freedom. There could be a contingency to favor one word, but the definition to a different note can hardly be ordained nor occasioned. Hence the concept can share a same attribute and meaning to denote a certain state or human condition that the personal autonomy would be protected by the absence of coercion and their desire can be in comport with their moral standard to act for or forebear from something. The concept of freedom would be attractive to gear up toward a new discourse of liberty or freedom beyond the dualism and other classic controversy entrenched in the wake of history. Nowadays, the comprehension of liberty proposers or critique rather focuses on the overall aspect of human condition so that they detest to be exorbitant in the dealings of analytical philosophy. Hence, the comparative stance between the societies may be one of useful attitudes for them. They also suspect if the three variables or triadic views of “agent, constraints, and purposes” could still be powerful in taking account of the contemporary issues or dilemma involved in the liberty. Their concern may be driven in any more intense level to see whether the agent is “actually doing certain things in certain ways” (2013). For example, the people of China or North Korea may trouble with the liberty or freedom, and cannot be comprehended in any clarified way to assess their problem. Are they free on the popular use of internet or can they actually be free to express an opposing view or to critique the legitimacy of their regime? Are they actually residing within a decent housing from the minimum standard of human condition? This kind of overall and consequential ways to assess would be phenomenological and useful on the realistic ground. A merely different focus on variables or extension of them across the respective theory would be inefficient or mislead to the fallacy of concept. The concept of overall freedom would presume the absence of any kind of constraints whatsoever on the realization of one’s true self. In other words, the absence of all factors that could prevent the action x would be triggered, in the view of Green and Bousanquet, leading to the elimination of elementary confusion and convergence toward the whole of free or liberal person (2013). The Liberty and Freedom or Other Concept Despite this feeble use in distinction, the liberty and freedom may well be in contrast with the concept of license as Locke ascribed. He elicited that a license ill deserves the name of confinement which hedges us in only from bogs and precipices” (2013; Second Treatise, parags. 6 and 57). A liberty would often tackles the universal context of human condition and the state of personhood, which generally squelch the sectarian concern to any discriminatory effect. It would go otherwise if a license means the kind of authorization to qualify the sectarian liberty or freedom to do something. For example, any business license, driver’s, or professional license to practice their expertise would pertain to this scope of freedom. It may assume some of special factors to contravene the universal context of liberty or freedom on the general basis. The concept of license or charter and incorporation for the business http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Chrysippus http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Self-determination 66 corporate, later subsidized the capitalist economy and amenable to the national control in any uniform fashion and about the factors. It represents a part of human state, but can chill the scope of agent’s liberty. Therefore, it entails an attribute of positive liberty if to examine the internal factors in the purpose of analysis. It often is directed to the dimension to do something freely and intervene to coerce the unlicenced agent to forebear. Furthermore, the bar ethics and standard of practice, for example, often require to maintain a level of integrity and professional morality. Over the history, a dualism on the positive and negative liberty perhaps would impose a highest tension between the liberal and communist scheme of governance or polity. One point of contention underlies the exploitative nature of capitalist economy. In the occasion of bar license, I like to mention the context of working and compensation method on a hourly basis in the law firms. They are paid on the hours for which they are working. The law firms often operate on the basis of partnership agreement, and they liquidated on the fare share for each partner. As coupled with the hourly charge, the law firms, perhaps if they be a small firm, may offer the kind of model and prototype of work mode, to marginalize any extent of exploitation possibility. In the political approach of liberty, some may perceive that the work mode of such law firms, as in Mondrean or cooperatives, may mediate the extent of universal generalization concerning the liberty. Of course, the waged lawyers in the big scale law firm may not develop in this way. Nowadays nobody would suspect if the license to practice law would narrow the scope of liberty or the licensee deserves the name of confinement as a skilled machine on law. Therefore, the concept of liberty in this advanced civil society has pose an intertwined and compounded panorama to stream over the pluralistic dimension or sectors and society. 67 Reference Crocker, L.H. (1980). Positive Liberty: An Essay in Normative Political Philosophy (Melbourne International Philosophy Series), New York, NY: Springer. Graff, J. (1985). Adapting interiors and furnishings for the disabled, Madison, WI: University of Wisconsin—Extension. Kee-ryong, K. (2002). A Free Mobility of Disabled in Korea, The Citizenry and Lawyers. Seoul, ROK: Seoul Bar Association. Laureate Education Inc. (2003). Ethics and Social Justice "Human Rights: Applications" with Amanda Baker (approximately 8 minutes). Murphy, A. (1998). Reason, Reality, and Speculative Philosophy. Madison WI: University of Wisconsin Press (1996). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy : Positive and Negative liberty, Retrieved as of Oct. 25 2013 from http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rights-human/. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rights-human/ 68 XII. Liberty and Public Organizations The Assessment System of Court and KBO’s Policy The Korean Bar Association (KBA) and court as well as the prosecution offices are triadic branches to sustain the Korean legal system. The court is particularly placed to serve the administration of justice and assumes the role to protect the human rights. It functions and execute the judicial power as a constitutional organ. It is responsible to adjudicate on the cases and controversies, and redresses the grievances arising from a legal dispute. Korea has a dual supremacy in judicial terms between the Constitutional Court and ordinary courts. One of organizational policy to interact with the liberty interest of judge would be the assessment system for the tenure review. In order to attain an institutional goal for the fitness and character review of judges, the assessment system often is regarded indispensable. However, it could deviate, in practical effect, from the policy objective, but to obstruct the independence of judiciary and eclipse a full-fledge exercise of conscience, individual or professional conviction (Laureate Education Inc., 2013). Given the nature of meritocracy deeply rooted in the personnel affairs, it assists by advising on and informing a requisite assessment. Since it could be misused to exclude certain judges who are conscientious, but politically dissidents, it often would be raised as a public concern about the commitment of judicial independence. This would be same when we consider a budgetary subjectivity of Judiciary to the Executive. While the liberty of judges would arguably be lawfully restricted on his official duty, the term, liberty, could be apprehended in any organizational, not in a strict legal sense, or informal leeway to administer his personality. For example, some excessive pressure to use a decent word in the bar or to enforce a courteous conduct to serve the sovereigns in loyalty and public trust may bring a tiresome or inefficient outcome in the administration of justice (KBA, 2011). Most problematic is that the assessment system may undermine the professional integrity by forcing them to comply with in his promotion or retention wish. So his or her secular interest on the promotion and retention of office can distort his inner side of moral conviction or due way to be personally held. This personal preserve of mental and intellectual disposition or conviction would be a very strand on which the judicial organs are presumed on. Hence the infringement with a conscience or belief of judges would lead directly to unsettle the judicial independence. The liberty issue then approaches in the same structure about the conscientious objector or anti- war vigils. The court has managed long years the assessment system and graded judges who are to be referred to the tenure review. However, a dominantly conservative ethos and public monitor about the judicial independence or suspect on the system, its practical impact would often be minimal and an automatic renewal for another ten tenure years sees no difficulties for grant. The public attitude has improved to identify the pros and cons of system, and the concept of democratic servant-ship recently has been emphasized to secure a loyal and faithful quality of judges. Also the peer pressure to ensure a fair and democratic quality between the counsels and judges at bar would grow, and could be correlated with such popular attitude. These situational variables affected the culture and ethical paradigm of court judges, and KBA, since 2010, instituted a regular process, on the annual basis, to complement with the assessment system of Court. KBA launched a peer survey to collect the opinion about the judges on the list of tenure review during 8 days, from Jan. 6 through 17. KBA 69 announced its background to meet the end to cross-confirm the personnel powers of the Chief Justice (2011). It pointed to the potential flaws that CJ exercises a plenary power to grant the long years of tenure. This kind of institutional vulnerability actually factored to yield no case of renewal denial which makes the process autonomous and meaningless. Some unethical judges who are verbally abusive in bar communication or indecent to provoke a shame for the clients could not be filtered according to the public report of KBA. This undermined a public trust for the judiciary, and KBO claimed that it was the most objective, relevant, and competent agency to assess the judges. The peer survey was conducted to cover 153 judges on the list of 2011 tenure review (2011). Over 1017 attorneys at law participated which was starkly gross than a previous occasion. 79 judges were found to be defaulted for an entitlement of new tenure. 74 judges were rated superior and qualified for the renewal. The grounds to make up such an impeachment would be, in rank order, the authoritarian or charismatic attitude (45 votes), bias, prejudice, predisposition, and abusive verb or behavior (25 votes). The Liberty of Public Officers and Organizational Integrity In furtherance about the liberty and transgression of assessment policy, I may brief on the public fear or excessive attention on the ideological propensity of judges. Korea is a divided country on this very reason between the leftists and right wing. Often we see it desirable that the court would be composed of diverse judges to represent a social philosophy. This context was seriously suppressed not by the governmental intervention but by such enthusiastic Right Civil Association in Korea (Chosun.Com, 2011). They often would be veterans, middle class of conservative ethos, and those who have a family background to detest North Korea. This created the social circumstances, which may be received as the kind of societal expectations for judges as in the Cooper’s components on responsible conduct (Cooper, C.T., 2011). Hence, they could be affected, and his personal interest on the promotion or retention of public office, in combination with the assessment system, may facilitate the inner process to convert his conscience to a prevailing ethos. This not only abridges the liberty of judges, but also could adversely touch on the core theme of judicial independence and social diversity. The internet portal of Chosun, often viewed as a most strong Korean conservative, hints on this point, “It is a constitutional mandate that judges are amenable to the tenure review for every ten years, who will not be dismissed from the office, but only on the causes exclusively of impeachment from the Congress and criminal conviction leveled above a confinement penalty. The Court Administration of Korea has not been practical to play a minimal role with the perfunctory apparatus of assessment system and tenure review. The tenure system was introduced in 1988, but only five judges during 25 years were denied a tenure” (2011). This quote was complemented by other conservatives so that they perceived this phenomenon serious about the rise of leftism adhering judges. Their tone and criticism has been acid that this lack of proper institution or flawed policy implementation would lead the Republic to collapse. They also expressed a concern of fear if the leftist judges could influence to shape the policy of Supreme or Constitutional Court. Now the public criticism surges to deprave the last election about the political intervention and unfair context of election campaign. It poses serious challenges for the president, ruling party and conservative group that the allegedly leftist circle now are legalized to plan a massive candle vigil in the public place. In their view, the Constitutional Court, in a last case dealing with the US imported mad cows, deplorably has dispatched a generous policy about 70 the right to assembly and demonstration in the public street. In their version, this outcome, of course, would show a weird network with the leftist powers in the judiciary (2011). The threat or evil from the assessment system and KBA’s policy could be illustrated convivially in the case of Kee-ho Seo, who was a middle age judge and alleged to uphold the virtue of leftist ideals. He also has been notorious to lead an e-critique on the court leadership and prevailing judicial policies. He was a recent judge to be dismissed on the ethical ground. His accusation was examined based on the assessment system, but the grades were found to be assigned as misled by the subjective stance of his higher authority. Objectively, the amount of caseload and the rate to dispose or complete would range above the middle of whole judges. He later exploited another career as a congressman, and now is incumbent to impanel within the Government Audit and Hearing Session in 2013. The Benefit of System/Policy and Their Prospect In any way, the assessment system and KBA’s policy likely would sustain ahead in view of its fundamental role about the personnel affairs, quality and character of judges and democratic practice in the consort with KBA. Seung-tae Yang was appointed as a Chief Justice of Korea on Jan. 18, 2011. The nominee was roiled into an interview of public media, and made a brief comment, “most capable judges would be the ones who deserve the public trust.” In broach to this comment, he adverted, “the public trust should be more hardly achieved other than legal research or knowledge.” In his view, the judgment has to be tempered and consonant with the common sense of justice and shared apprehension (Laureate Education Inc., 2013). This would be any authentic role of judiciary so that the clients could be persuaded. In Korea and perhaps universally, a miscarriage of finding the facts or implausible criminal sentence often would be the point of contention and dissuasion. The parties and his counsel would be a most knowledgeable person about the case. The counsels are qualified as a matter of law to represent the party and could share a common step on the progress of litigation. He would be virtually same to the party in the disposition and sensibility about the case. Hence, to obtain his respect and sharing would be really imploring. In this light, KBA’s policy to factor the assessment system could complement its flaws, which is a statutory mandate and overly indispensable (KBA, 2011). Some of court critique perceives it improper since it is odd for the players to evaluate an umpire. The Supreme Court still is reluctant to use the survey result as any definite variables in managing the official assessment system. As said, however, it seems most plausible and convincing to recourse the counsels, a direct peer of court judges, in assessing their quality, integrity, and personality or propensity. It directly is connected to build in the public trust. This policy may be expanded to cover the prosecution offices in Korea. As for its organizational nature of quasi- judiciary, the public trust is urged as a pivotal value than any other governmental branch. This actually underlies in an organizational concept that the key leaders of organization often reiterated to implant its ultimatum. Unfortunately, its genuine implications and moral requirement have been neglected. Now the people are suspicious if KPO were to be committed seriously to improve its poor image on public trust. A meaningful change has been noted recently so that now a large number of criminal cases on a statutory complaint basis are litigated with the counsels being appointed. This phenomenon would be in the sharp contrast than in past ten years. Counsels could be an agent to be fully aware of the client’s satisfaction. They could be more usable to ground the genuine basis of assessment than the previous system, mere a KPO survey of clients. 71 Reference Chosun.Com (2011).Judges and Korean Society. Seoul, South Korea. Cooper, C.T. (2011). The Responsible Administrator, San Francisco, CA: Josey Bass. KBA (2011).Internet Newspaper of Lawyer. Seoul, South Korea. Laureate Education Inc. (2013). Ethics and Social Justice"Liberty: Applications" with Amanda Baker (approximately 7 minutes). 72 XIII. The Organizational Culture, Policy and Ethics The Society and General Aspect of Organizational Culture An ethics and responsible administration now draw any more popular attention in history. There is a scope of variables to bring this context of societal phenomenon. First, the public monitor and pressure activities have become increasingly active and flourishing to advocate the democratic process of politics. As the theme of democratic government deepens and becomes well settled, the bureaucrats turn to be assumed and required to be loyal with the servant-ship to the sovereign people. It can be traced back to early years of new Republic so that Andrew Jackson defines their peer or political group as common men (Cooper, C.T. , 2012). The prevailing view in earlier politics, as we can note, may well be a spoils of victory to staff and administer their governance. This tradition may still wedge in the presidential system, but the cleavage, in another dimension, can be ascertained. An ethics as a fiduciary servant and the imagery of loyal public administrators would be highlighted in the more systemic way in the proposition of Max Weber. Around the industrialization turbulence, he perceived the importance of social factors to sustain a right direction of capitalistic growth in the western society. The continental morality and new frontier of material advancement were engrafted to inculcate the due course of social evolution rooted in the western tradition. Hence, his requirements in ethics and morality about the honorable bureaucrats are practically plausible to account for a realistic exposure and value guides to vitalize on the capitalistic system of statecraft. The press and public media also may interplay to ensure the Weberian virtue by imposing a criticism and monitoring activities. The advancement of e-technology and revolutionary impact of social media or other communication culture also contributes to the increased public attention on the ethics of public employees. A civilian recourse has developed into the “hands and palpable breaths” of the political or social elites in pursuit of social justice and procuring their loyalty. The ruling elites now are circumscribed in any distinct environment of disclosure and strains. Once seen as mere a gossip, the social culture may no longer tolerate an ethical or insensible public decision making with the readily organized force of civil group. A democratic apparatus on the liberal concept of constitution also increases its profile and scope, for example, recognition of the right to know as one of fundamental rights. It is to be noted, however, that there are differences, according to Cooper, in a practical effect among the public tools, such as the code of ethics or law and public media (2012). Second, the public administration itself has been on the trajectory to fortify its discipline as a science with the assistance of modern psychology and sociology. A theme concerning the act of ethical management began to feature in an increasing profile since Bowman published the article titled “the ethical issue for the public manager.” Don Menzel developed this concern by imploring on the systemized and consistent effort to promote ethical organizations (2012). The ethics and responsible administration often would be impacted by several institutions in the combined force including law, history and organizational mission. This would generate a certain of organizational culture in which we derive the essential factors in coverage of normative structures, referent others, obedience to authority, and responsibility for consequences. As I refrain from first person in academic writing. adverted, the society witnesses the changing circumstances in fashion to recourse their public avenue of sovereign role. This larger environment may lead to a new shape of factors. For example, obedience to authority, in some cases, may shift that the civil monitor group could be more pressing and be viewed as the kind of authority to compromise. A 73 responsibility for consequences, in some cases, may be upstaged as deviated from the responsibility chain of line authority. For example, a Congressman in Korea may fear from the public opinion more than the Congressional Ethics Committee and its guidelines. Turning to the discipline, it is highly advisable to ensure the integrity and continued ethical practice that the ethical decision makers plan on and design a scientific model, as the Cooper’s model illustrates, and prevents a self- serving attitude of bureaucrats and public administrators (2012). Other useful framework would be the Person-situation Interactionist Model developed by Trevino (2012). According to that model, public employees may process on the stages beginning with the ethical dilemma, cognitive stage and through the ethical or unethical behavior. The model identified four scores of influence to reach an ethical decision, which incorporates the individual attributes, immediate job context, organizational culture and characteristics of work. It also elicited subelements with respect to each dimension. For example, the individual attributes are determined by assessing the field dependence, ego strength, and locus of control. The Organizational Culture and Organizational Policy Making As sketched, the organizational culture would presume a general ambit through the specifics of organization. It is a societal creature to be rooted in the history, tradition, moral and ethical virtues to be implanted in the bureaucracy and organizations. The changing circumstances on an increasing intensity or compression of society as brought by the technological development as well as popular control along with the increasing power of public media, all accounts for the new shape of organizational culture. The issue of whistleblower, its moral basis and argument, as well as its protection as a public policy plainly proves the upstaged or societal context of organizational culture. In light of the specifics of organization, we need to note the importance of scientific contribution leading to the understanding of ethical or unethical behaviors as well as policies. For example, the Lucifer effect can elucidate the individual character traits and organizational culture as well as other situational variables (2012). The Trevino’s model also employs the organizational culture in four elements as an important variable which brings an ethical behavior or policy making. In this way of thinking, we may infer two dimensions of focus and in the primacy of attention which are elaborated by Finer and Friedrich (2012). Finer emphasized the role of external controls so that the law and code of ethics must be ensured in proper terms and in the nature to control the organizational members to adhere with their ethical requirement. Friedrich rather stressed on the practical importance of internal factors enshrined in individuals. Hence the ethical policy making or behavior would hardly be achievable without any genuine submissiveness to the ethically required way of behavior or conduct. His view, therefore, shed an intense weight on the learning and developmental program for the policy makers or administrators. Remember paragraphing is important to separate points. Otherwise, the reader does not know when a point begins and one ends. If the elements cherished by both camps are not mutually exclusive, they often become concrete in one concept of organizational culture by way of law, history, mission as well as a basic tone of the civilized understanding of public organizations. Of course, the organizational culture may be taken distinctively due to its nature and quality. For example, the Finer’s qualm may have a nuance between the legislative assembly and normal bureaucratic structure (2012). The latter may be more meddling on discretion to favor doubt while an ethical pattern of the latter case often likes to clarify the course of ethical 74 deliberation in the face of public monitor. Hence, the former case would be more amenable to the Weberian concept about limiting a discretion in ways to prevent the civil servant’s remonstrances and to place them in order. In the standing point of view, if the organizational culture needs to be examined from ethical policies, the critical inquiry would be if the organization now operates in the symptom of nonfeasance, malfeasance, and overfeasnace (2012). The Korean Judiciary, Organizational Culture and KBA’s Policy For the purpose of illustration, I consider a recent public focus on the courtesy and ethical behavior of judges, public prosecutors and counsels in the court proceeding. The area of ethics often stems from the professional code of conduct, but, in some cases, related with the criminal response on the contempt of court. They share an enhanced level of covenant as if they fall within the notion of New Adminsitration Movement, so that the smacks of professional eliticism and the concept of “client other than citizens” may apply to explain their status (Cooper, C.T., 2012). The virtues prevailed in the Movement, such as courage, commitment to human values and integrity espoused by E. Dvorin and R. Simmons, could also be the point of sanctity to be respected in the Korean case while some technical standard and specifics will combine to effect in producing an acceptable course of ethical behavior (2012). While the civil power has traveled over the sectors of society in enhancing a compliance with the democratic ethics, the Korean Bar Association erected an assessment policy of judges about their attitude and manner in the courtroom (Camp, J.C.V., 2005; Phillips, F., 2004). The assessment report was regularly disclosed to the public attention that poorly graded judges may suffer a disadvantage in the promotion and decision-making of personnel matter. In the last years, one judge committed a verbal abuse to the party by stating an indecent word. He allegedly affronted an aged party in the civil dispute, who was incompetent to delay the court schedule and had a less sense to present his case, by saying, “If a man turns to be aged, it might be better to die.” One other case involves a similar misconduct so that a presiding judge in the divorce proceeding libeled, “you would get awakened to see your spouse in the same bed with other males.” There are many other examples revealing an abusive or indecent communication with the parties. It seriously disparages the human esteem of client who, in this case, would be the party on the ride of civil service about any justice administration. The organizational culture of Korean judiciary, as in many other foreign examples, has long been distinctive on the dominant flavor of conservative ethos (2005; 2004). The judges would often be respected as honorable, and the ethics are often required of the citizen, or clients to maintain his honor over the court proceeding. The Japanese imperial rule, in early of 19th century, impacted profoundly on the organizational culture of court. That exposes a court scene that the judges look a kind of authority or charisma with the robe dressed up. His statement would be authoritative to direct, command and reprimand the parties and audience. The spirit of public service massively retreats as focused on the requirement of authority and respect of law. A liberty interest often safeguarded to ensure a human dignity, an ultimate destination for all purposes of national constitution and enacted in the Art. 10 of Korean constitution, was directly or indirectly affected (Laureate Education Inc., 2013). For example, an indicted suspect may be suppressed by a possibly overwhelming conduct or words which divert them from fully exploiting a due chance to defend his case. The judges in Korea, in some cases, may carry a wrong form of short court opinion that fails to fully disclose the points of contention and court opinion on the respective issue. This ethical failure, as reported in the 75 last news paper story, may jeopardize the context of party’s right to appeal and the client’s satisfaction (Camp, J.C.V., 2005; Phillips, F., 2004). While there is a separate view about the liberty or human rights viewpoint, the public employees often are conceived as a special group and fall outside the scope of protection. For example, it would be answered in a limited scope of recognition if the government employees enjoy the freedom of expression. The judges and prosecution officers would also be deemed as a natural person entitled to the scope of constitutional protection. The new policy from KBA may infringe upon the liberty interests of judges, but the prevailing view would likely be reluctant to shed on that strand in this case. Some Solutions for the Ethics of Judges Assuming that the Cooper’s decision model is to be exploited in phases and specifics of this illustration, I now could comment on some of the ethical standard as a solution for the concerned parties (Cooper, C.T., 2012). First, the courtesy of “bowing and saying hello” needs to be revisited. The counsels to travel a corridor or courtroom had been usual to nod their head in ways to pay a recognition and respect. This courtesy seems still practiced in the local district, but the buzzing environment of Seoul may have changed on the practice. Now only a small number of attorneys in Seoul follow this routine way to elevate the professional integrity and sharing. This change of personal ethics may be due to the increasing number of new entrants to the profession. The number tripled in the past decade. The lesson from the American scene may be practical where a predicate “Your Honor” is held uniform to refer to the judge. This ethics can increase the public respect and trust in the end of strengthening the rule of law concept. Second, the examination or cross-examination procedure requires the counsels to comply with an impartial, speedy and decent process purported by the law and professional ethics. It needs to be discouraged or banned to disparage the integrity of prosecution authorities which is impertinent to the facts or profile of cases. Often counsels may complain in informal ways to tarnish the prosecution decision as irrational or attack an ill aspect of criminal practices. It entails a serious deviation if the accusation involves an imprecise or wrong fact. For another, it needs to be avoided to intervene in the process of examination or cross-examination. It would be ethical to wait for its completion of prior interrogatory and proceed to his case. An attitude to examine the witnesses also needs to be put to improvement and correction. It is unethical and contradicts to the covenant of democratic rule if the counsels behave in the authoritative or indecent manner. Often an oral statement not taken care of can affront and insult the witnesses. Other ill aspect may be perceptive on the technical standard so that opinion-seeking inquiry or questions about the immoral character of witness would be improper and in violation of the ethical codes. Third, the court judges need to be modest and common so that they never behave pretending to be potent or mightier to teach the counsels. This point would be emphatic about the removal of counsel’s grievance. They are common peers to administer the justice in collaboration and cooperation. Now the judges are no longer the class of public nobility. He or she, as a public administrator, needs to find his standard of conduct and workplace ethics from the virtues of American public administration, say, equality, freedom, beneficence, respect for individuals, popular sovereignty, and justice. This does not mean that the principal role of judges to shape an issue and marshal the points in contention could be derogated or disobeyed by the counsels. A bias or arrogance of judges as if in the step of prosecutor’s case and to squeeze the counsels in his ways or understanding would be problematic, especially in 76 the criminal proceedings. In some cases, it brings the consequence to break the fundamental assumption of party system by exceeding from the scope of indictment statement or prosecution’s claims. Reference Camp, J.C.V. (2005). Ethical Issues in the Courts: A Companion to Philosophical Ethics. New Tech Park, Singapore: Cengage Learning Cooper, C.T. (2011). The Responsible Administrator. San Fransico, CA: Josey Bass. Laureate Education Inc. (2013). Ethics and Social Justice "Liberty: Applications" with Amanda Baker (approximately 7 minutes). Phillips, F. (2004). Ethics of the Legal Profession Portland OR : Routledge-Cavendish. 77 XIV. On the Nature of Social Justice Issue Poverty and Homelessness in 1998’s South Korea Around the end of 1990’s, Korea had undergone a serious financial crisis, and the IMF role only could settle the unsavory condition of national economy. In these years, the poverty class in a ghetto, often unemployed and homeless, had posed the challenges to justice and deserved a social attention. As learned on Frederickson, a poverty also emerged to shift the traditional paradigm of public policy which concerns the race, gender and ethnicity in US (Frederickson, G., 2005). Its extent has gotten worse that the assumption for these elements to imply a poverty would be made inadequate in the face of a rising threat to the social justice in US. A social stratification now rolls back to call a more engaged attention beyond the narrative of diversity or multiculturalism. If the nature of social issue has a profile on the universal element of humanity, it would be a matter of our attitude or disposition rather than any evolution or progress in the time sequence. I mean if the kind of Maya or Inca civilization or others beyond the level of contemporary one, could flourish or perish in mystery, but could be plausible. As in a science film, we may have unknown a superior alien civilization in any other time, but may hardly be recovered into a reality for other reasons. The poverty issue may have been quite that of improved form in 1950’s than the current status. This area of public policy may bear such kind of irony that the attention or maintenance to mend in continuance as well as on constant watch to respond with would be necessary. The kind of apprehension, “the poverty in the past on this level, economic status and social welfare on progress over time, and the present status of poverty issue would be easy,” should not entertain as any convincing ways of thinking. As the concept of justice expounded in the Republic by Plato, the poverty may pose a serious challenge to the ruler and ethical administrator (SEP: Justice As a Virtue, 2013). It is related with the basic standard of humans, and very sensitive as sufficient to question the social justice, ethics, as well as legitimacy of polity. It has a root over the history as we can find a plethora of authority, i.e., the pleasure of moral person or ruler in Plato and Cicero, pleasure and the greatest happiness for the greatest number of people in Bentham’s case, a refined persuasion in German rationalism and Weberian ways of bureaucratic ethics, Rawl’s concept of justice, and even the functional equality or positive liberty circle for the social justice in most modern thinkers (SEP: Distributive Justice, 2013). In this line of thought, I may derive some of implications. First, the issue of social justice would be omnipresent across the polities both in time and geographic distribution. That is because the issue would be interwoven with the universal or human intrinsic and attribute. It could be conceptually shared in any common concern, and may not be submissive to any time rationale. The elapse of time and economic progress never absolutely mean an improvement of poverty in view of the social justice. Second, this aspect alerts the public administers, who are required to be courageous and vigilant to realize the social equity and justice. Now the system is not static which is unlike the aristocracy. As said, roundreasoning has been embedded to ground the human cause for social equity (Frederickson, G., 2005). W. Wilson’ stated, “it is harder to run a constitution than to invent it” (2005). As an implementation is urgent than policy making, it needs an extent of positive engagement. For example, the employers are to improve the hiring practices, which means even to touch on the human resource than mere implementation of social equity program, project and policy (2005). 78 The Status, Threat to Justice, and Factors to Address Poverty may well be conceived as a worst factor leading to the social injustice. It poses a fundamental threat to the justice of society. The poverty class would be often deprived of adequate public education, and the status could persist over the generations. They may economically suffer below the minimum standard of human subsistence. Their social and economic reproduction may be threatened that they often lack a due provision to function as a laborer. They may suffer in the street since they have no shelter, which contravenes a basic right to a decent housing in the commitment of UDHR. We may have a due kind of reference that UDHR would prescribe a standard on the current status of social justice. It is obvious that virtually no human can have a pleasure to face with the reality of homeless. How do we have a pleasant sleep if we have been disposed palpably on their case? The rulers and public administration would be responsible as we learn on the ethics, public value and other sources of moral administration (2005). In Korea, the unemployment rate has sharply increased in the first and third quarter of 1998, 5.7 percents, 6.8 percents, and 7.3 percents respectively (KBA, 1998). The so-called IMF crisis began in 1997, and the firms or enterprises executed massive layoffs in the initiative of rationalization of their business. According to the statistics of Labor Department, the Poor Household Loans for the unemployed sharply increased from 65.5 million dollars per month through 113.2 and 117.3 million at the end of year. This data implies that the unemployed began to exploit the governmental loans to subsidize their living. In other words, the subsidies and pension alimony could no longer support completely to meet their basic needs. The Labor Welfare Foundation also managed a public program about the unemployment loans, but the terms and conditions were tougher to frustrate many unemployed workers (1998). It was ambitious to rehabilitate all scope of unemployed workers, but the loans actually was provided only for eight cases during eight days in the year. This program has envisaged drawing the funds by marketing the unemployment settlement securities, but the goal proved impractical by selling only 12.8 percents of securities in the stock market. It affected an initial plan so that it was reduced seriously and viewed as one of critical policy failure. The government initially shaped the plan to create 270,000 jobs by inputting 544.4 million dollars, but the unexpected growth of unemployed required an additional allocation of funds in the same (1998). A public project committed to the increase of employment purported to ensure a basic right to subsist as well as create the jobs. The factors to be considered would be a marginalized pay, which would be a principal driver for the 3D (to avoid the dirty, dangerous and difficult jobs) vogue in the society. One other point in consideration is to frame an adequate policy vision and its operation in an interplay with the public aids and social welfare program, which were intended for an ineligible person from the unemployment insurance ambit. It is critical to systemize an institution to clarify whether or not the public project on labor, in its quality, is social welfare or labor based. The factors to be taken care of would be that the issue is familial as well as personal. Hence, the policy makers need to shed a light on the starved students in the school. Therefore, it could be timely to provide a free lunch from the next year, 1999 and could be afforded in the vacations. One difficulties lie in the status of schools about the availability of space and other practical strands, which troubled the uniform fashion of administration. The context of 1998’s Korea exhibited a serious injustice between the cause-arouser and victims of society. Many critiques 79 were conceived that the management and capitalist class could be culpable to bring the anomaly of national economy. However, the economic and social benefit for the Chaeboland haves inclined to expand while the lower income class was stigmatized to suffer. They were often deprived of a due status in the employment relations and could be dismissed without any due respect and at the will of employers. The distributive justice may well be seen seriously depraved by the dip between the haves and have-nots. The social injustice henceforth would come into any serious context. It then fell within the responsibility of public administration beyond the private sphere. Unless they were responded with adequately, they would get worse to a homeless status and the crime rate for economic reasons would likely double (Frederickson, G., 2005). A disorganization of family could frequent and harms on its value would be challenging. The foundation of society would be put into a jeopardy. Concerning the homeless issue in Korea, we consider two classes of homeless people between the long-settled vagabonds and dismissed employees in the close years of economic decline. As the latter class often are similar so as to falter from the social alienation, members of disorganized family, marginalized economic status, the classification would less powerfully serve the policy response. With respect to the national attributes of homeless issue, the temporal response to provide a labor opportunity or free meals are not seasonal to attain a more effective outcome. A major portion of homeless in Korea are the fifties in an age range, and the success of British case could give us a lesson. The practice to afford the social safety network in the United Kingdom would yield a best result than any other alternatives, which led to a drastic contrast of 1-2 percents in the age range of fifties. Hence, a systemic provision leading them to rehabilitate as well as the housing welfare program would be seriously explored in the forefront of decades (Frederickson, G., 2008). The Concept of Justice and Social Equity Justice and social equity often arose to be public ideals that the respective branches of government pursue and undertake to struggle through their professional lives. Two dimensions in structure or in the least some of hypothesis other than this preserve would be a politics and civil capitalism. The politics or political science would concentrate on the power, structure of government, political process as well as the virtues or criticism that the specific or universal context of political community need to be addressed or contended. In view of the rule of law or public administration, they would rather be akin to the creation of laws than implementation of them. The views of W. Wilson elicited appealingly, “it must be harder to run a constitution than to create it” (Frederickson, G., 2005). The ideals could be shared by both minds. However, the political scientists often would travel in any philosophical relativism so as to be submissive to the interest of their core theme, say, the political power. It often proves in a convincing force and tack of experiences that the public administrators, including the judges or lawmakers, particularly incumbents or those of majority parties, would be armed with the concepts and practice through their course of responsibility. Given a justice is received in the sort of social quality, the two concepts would be related in any same tone, logic or metaphor leading the ethics of public administrator (Frederickson, G., 2008). Both concepts have projected into the western intelligence as a persistent and enduring guide to practice the ethics of rulers which would hardly be traced nor supervened by other ideals. Monarchs, oriental or western notwithstanding, often recourse their daily business of politics in this way, and stressed the sublime status of justice or social equity although they might be more eagerly disposed to expand their terrain or threat to his might or 80 political power. The socialist states had been notable to cherish this logic, which would go farthest to entirely revolutionize the traditional virtue of Christianity or prevailing thought of Republicanism. The concepts have been embedded on the very notion of human disposition as we have been illustrated in the Cicero’s subscription to justice in fundament of his ruling philosophy. In the ancient times, justice may converge to the same destination between the ruler, who often would be one person and as discarding a check from the Senate, and political community. The ruler’s justice also would be a social one. The context would transform if the public governance began to practice on the free election, equal vote, and representative democracy. The deliberative nature of democratic tradition may negotiate to bridge the kind of conscience, justice, equity, often being ascribed to the absolute figure only, with the science, due process, as well as the traditional virtue of western society. Therefore, the two concepts would not differ, but come congruent to serve the realities of public governance, the ruling and ruled, ethics and community, and in compliance with the pleasure of ruler or that of citizenry as its equivalent in modern terms (Meyer, M., 2008). It could be antithetic to the general thesis of liberalism if to speak for the absolutism of pure market, and could be mediated in a lesser force if some stress the institution of free market as in Hayek and ground laws to support the system. As the laws become complicated in the public pressure and political voice, the social legislation would be coupled to impose an implementation of social equity. Hence, the public administrators in the contemporary society need to meet a dual challenge to address, which could be granted in any inviolable context and in ultimatum. Threats to Justice and Social Equity: Less Courageous In this structure, we derive two strands that they are shaped. First, as Frederickson mentioned, the public administration put any more strains and emphasis on the implementation of policy rather than the creation of them (Frederickson, G., 2005). Of course, they may develop their career later as a law maker or could serve more effectively. However, the policy implementation or the concept of law in action would be unique to be exclusively reserved for the group. His argument on the poverty and increasing inequality between the haves and have-nots are imminent for the public administrators to respond with (2005). His message is straightforward and reflexive since the antigovernmentalism is largely impractical at this point of time. His attribution about the basic propensity of American citizen, as philosophical conservatives and pragmatic liberals, seems to be generally universal in my surmise of global public (2005). Of course, still in contention can it be argued in the first prong, hence, we may go to ask what we like to conserve or make it inviolable. In any notable interplay or in general complacency about the demise of ideology, that question would often be dealt in a secondary profile or impossible to be resolved in any mutual agreements. Then the second prong would be operable to impose a duty or moral leadership to be subservient about. In this backdrop, the justice and social ethics would be defined to level their playing field on professionalism. It would be honorable objectives and the group has to be persistent and continued to mend it, not to end it. It perhaps would be the idealistic smacks of bureaucracy who should not tolerate sinful inequalities. The phenomenon, in Frederickson’s assessment, is serious so that it is important to ask for whom the policy or social program was addressed in any identifiable policy consequence (Frederickson, G., 2008). It is insufficient to point to the shape, codal language in mandate, structure of policy, often expressed in the form of statute and acts whether the social injustice was properly prescribed. Hence, the public administrators need to think about the three faculties as classed of knowledge, courage, and a quick wit. Often incompleteness or shortcomings are caused by 81 the lack of courage which is a major challenge in improving the current state of social ethics in the American society. Some Examples of Justice and Social Equity In consideration of the gaps on this point, and as illustrated in the street level bureaucrats, both concepts may be made distinct in epistemology, epithet, and in intellectual ways to develop the logic and metaphor (2008). As seen generally, both concepts could be used interchangeably, and trigger the same destination practically. The concept of justice, at the beginning point, bears two dimensions, which incorporate the individual and social strands. For the individual justice, the notion would often be posited in the respective condition and behavior of agent, which is processed in his inner mind about the moral issues having to do with goods or property. It may be questioned to probe its verity or ethics, however, as often deferred to be vested in that particular agent. Consider a father to kidnap his early child and abandons her in the deep mountain. Does he act on the terms and requirements of justice? We would not attack his act on its face that his act would contravene the moral or just requirement. He may suffer a worse poverty which drove him to have no way but to discard the early life. Other individual context of background may force him to choose or act. The concept of distributive justice may get closer to that of social justice, but the proposition employs an extent of historical, economic, philosophical, judicial, and political as well as experiential scholarship in flavor (SEP : Distributive Justice, 2013). The concept of social justice is a matter of societal concern and based on the science and statistics, which could be more tangible and beyond the idealistic posture or status. Hence, it anticipates an implementation as its companioned concept, social equity. The individual justice and social one may be independently set, but the marginal example can be convivial in the ancient sage of China, Mencius. Consider, in perversion from the first case, the adult pedestrian who found an early child who are about to be drowned in the river. Is it ethical or does it conform to the justice as Plato traveled in his book Republic? Mencius answered negatively unlike the former case and the courage is required as a moral agent. Mencius was a pro-goodness moral adherent while Xun zi would churn on the evil strand of humanity at its very bottom. Transpose, in hypothesis, the agent to be a father of drowning child. The moral requirement may shift across the society, and offers the source to be discussed intensely in the jurisprudence. We, therefore, can borrow the ideas in understanding the diverse viewpoints in bridging the justice, ethics and morality (Meyer, M., 2008). The Good Samaritan law also would be one example. As the justice entails this individual domain, it can operate as a useful concept to view the phenomenon and social mechanism. For example, the individual justice cannot be assumed if the agent is incompetent or minor. They, in a cogency and assumption, could not be deemed to make an ethical or moral decision. The criminal and civil laws recognize this understanding to institute a law in the case and statutory form. Social equity, as hinted, can possess an applied and phenomenological focus to make us possible on the grand picture of society. This light of dualism may be ascertained in the long practice of Court of Chancellery, what we often call an equity court. The common law court is often ascribed to defend the justice, which would be technical, detailed, party-specific, and inquisitive or probing. The Court of Chancellery would serve the will of sovereign to redress the injustice in a grand and fundamental stage. It may entertain the finality privilege from its character, but the modern court is structured and operates in the idea of division of labor. The social equity could be reinforced to correspond with the advent of democratic society, which would be owed to the development of modern science. For example, Comte’s positivism affected the 82 intellectual minds of society in any revolutionary influence, and enlightened new waves of thinking based on the objective science. A Relationship of Both Concepts The concept of justice would be useful to penetrate the politics, public administration, and law. It encompasses squarely the ambit of individual, social and administrative domain (SEP: Justice as a Virtue, 2013). In the public administration, both concepts would be combined to reflect. In reverting to the Frederickson’s point, the gap actually is problematic that the levels of administrators need to heed on precaution. As a policy implementer, the executives are one organ in assumption to penetrate the line authority in the destination to share the uniform concept of justice. The same context was posed in the theory of criminal justice system in Korea. Each prosecution officer is deemed in terms of its capacity and legal qualification as same in the uniform fashion about respective cases. They are responsible to the higher ranks in the sphere of public administration, but not in the level of quasi-judicial role. Their quasi-judicial role also manifests to deliver a specific justice so that I consider it to be received in any extent to awaken the less courageous bureaucrats or street level ones who could be biased or manipulative. In dealing with the cases, a junior prosecutor is same as the head of prosecution office. In remedying the social inequity and carrying their official power, they would do as same as the president or higher ranks. The concept of justice intrinsically is related with the basic attributes of humanity, and hence individual (SEP : Justice as a Virtue, 2013). As Cicero stated, it enshrines in the quality of ruler, whom the levels of policy administrators can be integrated into one ethics and moral direction despite a different mask. That said, we can understand the theory of vicarious liability where the court centralizes if the officer’s tort is perpetrated in the color of governmental function. Therefore, a scientific inquiry and policy implementation to secure the social equity can be tightened toward a justice. Both concepts swerve through the myriad of bureaucrats and moral administration, which may be leveled from the bottom, mid-ranks and top officers. In some cases, the kind of different institutions, as in the example of Court of Chancellery, may serve the cause of justice and based on the equity concept. As the science develops, their wisdom may respond with the shift in the public value and good. I may state that justice is more specific, individual, on the human-element science, universal, but dominantly national, and through all the ranks of administration while the social equity is grand, collective, often on the quantitative science, grouped, but both national and international, and often urged on the mid-ranks work force. Reference Frederickson, G. (2008). Social equity in the twenty-first century: An essay in memory of Philip J. Rutledge. Journal of Public Affairs Education, 14(1), 1-8. Frederickson, G. (2005). The state of social equity in American public administration. National Civic Review, 94(4), 3138. Korean Bar Association (1998), The Human Rights Report No. 14, Seoul, South Korea. Meyer, M. (2008). Revue Internationale de Philisophie - Volume 62 Number 246 - No 4 - 2008 (Aesthetics). Presse Universitaires de France. Paris. 83 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Justice as a Virtue. Retrieved Nov. 8, 2013 from http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/justice-virtue Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Distributive Justice. Retrieved Nov. 8, 2013 from http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/justice-distributive/. XV. Globalization and Workplace Dimensions and Lives of Public employees In dealing with the ethics and justice within the workplace, I consider two assumptions as important to be reified. The professionals would penetrate the ethics of workplace into its projected scale of policy outcome for the addressees and society. Then they share to be consistent to create a public good and value which the public administration ultimately pursues to realize. In the course of weighing and deliberation, the subtleties in distinction could be touched on. For example, the public administration can be made into an independent slot that a neutrality should be in primacy other than public policy making, a peer concept in this field. As Frederickson articulated, the segmented equality may variegate the terms and conditions of equity to be specific, cultural and pluralistic as well as even esoteric that would hardly be generalized (Frederickson, G., 1990). Therefore, equity to equities and equality to equalities are expected and even desirable to increase a fit of distributive justice in response with the sectors and societal progress or diversity. One thing may evolve into many things as challenges and opportunities for the public administrators. We may ascribe three elements for the administrators to tackle with, i.e., value preferences, organizational design preferences, management style preferences (1990). For example, the social equity would be intense as involved in the last one. However, we need to ask in fundament, “Do we steal popular sovereignty?” I revert to say that this does not necessarily require that the two dimensions, workplace and policy object in span, have to be severed for breeding them into dual minds and attitudes. Still are the elements to converge, and they integrate the workplace and exterior object as a policy addressee from the projected ethics. Basics, rules and principles can well stay universal and inviolable that they have to ultimately respect (Sandel, M. J., 2010). The smacks of bureaucratic professionalism, henceforth, often are habituated with the same tone, manner, errand and mission to be a cult in both planes. Often the public would be outrageous if the public enterprises, particularly high ranks of justice institution, commit to speak of verbal abuse against the females or a racially minority group. That would differ in sensibility and expectations of conscientious citizen if any other entities of private nature have been engaged. Once President Obama expressed a concern and regret about the unlawful killing of minor black boy, who was sacrificed from the prejudice and recklessness by the police on public duty. Consider if the American society stands on the public value, such as equality and liberty as signified in the Statue of Hudson River. I believe that this concept needs to be consistently upheld through the public commitment even in view of a personal imagery or impression as well as knowledge, skills, conscience and courage. The White House speech may be misimpressed how the black president can make an affirmative statement for the same race. I consider it pivotal to make the public emphatic on the American commitment to http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/justice-virtue http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/justice-distributive/ 84 the liberty and equality. This kind of consistent multifacetism, what may be seen a respectful catch-all professionalism through the personal lives, workplace justice, and a policy making or administration for the community, could make it improved and appealing, and diminish a public distrust or potential criticism of showcase administration. It would be idealistic if the public employees could be a living legacy to be constantly diligent for the commitment of public service. It then can make himself, organization and his followers identical and armed with the public values they pursue. Globalization as the Workplace Environment, and Public Governance In rethinking the workplace justice, the neo-liberalization in some combined influence with the globalization may directly or indirectly affect the shape of organizational ethics and justice paradigm or practice. As seen in the message of Mittelman, public governance could have any more potential and possesses a diverse spectrum to give an answer to the global restructuring and counteractive response (Mittelman, J. H., 2002). The states had been contested in the absolute logic of economy, so that it brought about two points of ill consequence. In the first, economically deprived or uncompetitive entities could no longer survive. In other, the national politics are to be enslaved into the global logic of capitalism, which increased a prestige of capitalists or conceptually leading states, being done in tradeoffs of the wane side of Asian or Latin American leadership (2002). As the driving force to an economic interest would be any more powerful than other social factors and on grassroots from an universal motive, it can gainsay any other competing alternatives. His prediction about the important role of public governance could be received in parallel with his suggestion, say, organic intellectuals. A tension and context would be inextricable given the stalemate and some of inefficiencies within the free market system or market failure. I agree on his point about the stellar mediating roles from the organic intellectuals and enhanced concept of public governance (2002). In this understanding, we would not become a fool attempting to rewrite a globalization script. The new paradigm of public governance would not tolerate a courtesan role within which the sleeping states would have passively reacted. It would be based on the constructive friendship to discuss, share and implement on consensus. One ambitious scheme may be found in the Labyrinthine Tobin’s tax, which may face with tough challenges from the local reaction. It may be idealistic as in the neo-liberal experimentalism, but rather abstract or principled with lacking a quality of public governance and enforceability. His proposition would be received as same as the concept of glocalization, but his thesis has persuasively maturated a picture of that experiment. He enabled us to have a histography about the application of neo-liberal tenet, particularly based on the experiences and exposure to such vulnerable region. The nations, for example, South Korea, Malaysia, Russia, Mexico, Brazil, and others, were studied in view of its wake of financial crisis (2002). He considered it some way to discipline those in the scheme to adjust for a new structure of neo-liberal market economy. IMF conditionalities and currency speculation would be two examples to be remarked in impression. A power deflation, in his view, is coupled with the overwhelming economic cause about its hardship, which even dismantles some of area on the embedded commitment by the national policy makers or public administrators. Erstwhile public functions could be discouraged or offset to remedy the dystopia of free market institution (2002). Therefore, the tension between the haves and have-nots has stood out within the 85 course of evolution over the decades. The contemporary dealings enable to witness the possibility of global public governance, as we see in Davos forum and many rounds of summitry, i.e., G8 or G15. His suggestion, while I also consider as workable and practical, for new understanding of public governance in the present context employs three strands, to say, organic intellectuals, self-determination or autonomy, and cooperation or pluralism of financial affairs. Japanese Students and Workers in South Korea For the example of workplace justice, I may think about Japanese students in Chosun University. Japan is an adjacent country, and both countries developed mutually a rich history in commerce, war, and imperialistic rule during early half of the past century, as well as new constructive partnership in some of mixed national sensibilities on antipathy and cooperation. This example would be helpful in reflection with the above promenade in the ethics of administration and globalization. The diasporadic cluster of Japanese community in Korea recently flourished in many localities of Korea. This would be owed to the globalization and enhanced mobility of labor force. Hence, how we perceive and govern this group of people would raise a serious aspect of public governance, which may be keenly related with the kind of segmented equality in the Frederickson frame. It could bring a diversity in the workforce, and the basic commitment on social equity and equality of liberty also are entangled with (Cropanzano, R., 2000). As they are workers of Japanese origin and may work in a different nature of organization, the equity into equities or segmented concept of justice can be embraced for the managers. The generic source of contention also deserves our review across the multiculturalism and effective or more efficient management or leadership. A justice could be prescribed which depends on the Korean authority, and organic intellectualism or autonomy within the globalized arrangement may intervene for the proper shape of workplace justice. In this light, the sociological, psychological or cultural studies about the Japanese community in Korea could offer a useful reference to make a specific justice for this group. Societal Expectations from the Cooper’s and Some Solutions As we learn, Cooper framed a useful paradigm which could lead to a responsible conduct for ethical governance. It covers four elements to interact for shaping a responsible conduct, which are multiple to affect and dimensional as classed into the individual attributes, organizational culture, organizational structure and societal expectations. By waiving other elements, I intend to parcel out the last slot to address the ethical challenges and work place justice. The last slot, societal expectations, would possess the quality as universal and for all scope of organizations although the Japanese workers involve an esoteric nature of bilateral interplay within the national passion or emotion, political and historical resentment, and cultural differences. Other three elements could make it distinct the process of forming an ethical decision and responsible conduct in varying with the purpose of their stay in Korea and organizational culture or structure. In the updated statistics, the Japanese community within Korea has grown, and most of Japanese residents are reported to engage in any quality job, such as research, teaching, technical assistance, professional work, and so (Lim, Y.E. & Huh, S.T., 2012). The purpose of stay would fall in comparison between the male and female workers as shown in the chart below. 86 (Figure) Natio n Sex Trade and Managemen t Universit y professor Japanese instructo r Researc h Technical counselin g Professiona l work Entertainmen t and arts Japan Male 59 147 104 335 5 5 24 Femal e 0 77 258 11 0 0 8 How to address the workplace justice and create any specific ethical decision, as we confirm, highly depends on the types of organization and its mission or work frames, as well as its culture and structure. It requires, however, of proper response to the societal expectations. As the workplace is educational and pursues a philanthropic errand to teach, breed, and research, the equal treatment, social equity and non-discrimination would be cherished and should be shaped in response with the societal expectations. The public administrators, in this aspect, need to heed on the segmented strands which could possibly counteract that important public value, i.e., the workplace equality on aliens. First, the antipathy among two nationals may distort their due status which could threaten a fair treatment. From the qualitative research on an in-depth interview, the Japanese residents, of course including the students in Korea, would suffer a fear and apprehension from some less friendly attitude of Koreans. As Cohen and Safran elicited, the history is a primary source to offer the personal trauma of diaspora, particularly originated from the kindred-ship, national identity and trauma to disperse. In the interview, one aged Japanese male lamented, “some Koreans are friendly and benevolent, but a large number of them are not sympathetic or alienating perhaps because of sad imperial history” (2012). Second, the worse factors to affect an equitable treatment also are related with the false understanding of history and a chronic contention of real issues, such as high school history textbooks, comfort women, and territorial claims of Dokdo, as also noted Takeshima in Japanese. This aspect must be a focal point in education and in the purpose of increasing a mutual awareness (2012). It also would be the strategic subject to create a harmonious ethos among workers and students, as well as a peace in the work place. It could be a precursor to induce the discriminatory consequence against the Japanese students or workers, which has to be tactically responded with. An education and informal fraternity could work for the congruent workplace in justice and effective multiculturalism. Reference Cropanzano, R. (2000). Justice in the Workplace: From theory To Practice, Volume 2 (Applied Psychology Series), Mahwha NJ: Psychology Press. Frederickson, G. (1990). Public administration and social equity.Public Administration Review, 50(2), p228 (10p). 87 Lim, Y.E. & Huh, S.T. (2012), The Diasporadic Cluster of Japanese in South Korea, and its Cultural Identities, The Journal of Northeast Asia Research, Vol. 27. No. 2, Gwang-ju, ROK : Chosun University Press. Mittelman, J. H. (2002). Making globalization work for the have nots. International Journal on World Peace, 19(2), 1-23. Sandel, M. J. (2010). Justice: What's the Right Thing to Do? New York, NY: Farrar, Straus and Giroux. XVI. The Responsible Administration, Ethics and Justice: Two Illustrations from South Korea and Some Reflections about the Public Administration Studies The National Assembly of Korea and Nature of Organization I chose the National Assembly of South Korea (NASK) for the purpose of final assignment, and shall apply the hypothesis as well as typology of ethical analysis on philosophies and corners of ethical virtues. This work would include the ethical challenges seriously debated in the near past and present days of NASK. As a public policy student, I intend to frame recommendations to produce a better picture to resolve the conflict of ethics, and explore factors to affect an implementation (Hicks, D., 2013). I finally draw upon the outcome of suggestions. While linking the two cases with the philosophies and theories to ground an intelligent basis of public administrators, I will discuss two implications about the ethics and responsible administration within the collegiate body as well as new orientation of academic response to the changing world politics, economics and society NASK has long been an indispensable organ incorporated within the Korean constitution since 1948, and the practice or institutional tradition can be shared as same with the universal context. Even if the parliamentary system of government may be discarded by the constitutional drafters as in Korean cases, the assembly body, mutas mutandis, the Congress or Parliament would sustain for a public governance. This tradition would perhaps be more strong as in the Socialist states in Duma or National People’s Congress of People’s Republic of China. In a suggestion later drawn to bridge the Orient and West or Socialist to Liberal by focusing on the ethics of ruler and ruling class or social justice, it bears a perceptive implication that NASK operates as a collegiate body (Laureate Education Inc. a, 2013). This implies that the collegiate body, as structured within the constitutions, is indispensable and centralized in public administration. NASK can well be viewed to mostly share the universal qualities and attributes when we surf onto other global bodies in any comparative politics or constitutional study. It is chaptered in the first of government structure in the Korean constitution, comprised of the elected congressman, exclusive legislative power and supervisory role to monitor other governmental branches, privileges and immunities ascribed to the members, the fixed constitutional term on their service, restrictions in double-posting and so. 88 According to the Constitution, the election will be held in four years to reshuffle a previous body and for the new term. The last election was held in 2012, and was denoted as the 19 th congress in the constitutional history of Korea. The election requires the members directly chosen by the people, but some quota basis approach was introduced to assign the members based on the total number of votes for a respective political party. Sanenouri, the ruling party of Korea, had been successful to achieve a majority status in the last election. Minjoo (democratic party in English), a major opposing party, also acquired a fair number of seats able which became able to influence their political ethos and goal. Some groups may like to explore a constitutional reform, who advocate the parliamentary system of government, but merely hover around the academics or distinct group of politicians. NASK currently operates under the 1987 Constitution based on the presidential system, and the chance to transform would largely be seen improbable in any recent years. Hence, NASK is generally considered to execute their constitutional mandate on the separation of powers principle, which only takes a part to integrate the national policy, neither a center of government unlike the parliamentary system. However, the party system often dominant in the contemporary politics would mediate the president and NASK, which also would be a case in Korea. As the social justice and virtue of Republican democracy still largely are the factors of political contention despite the commonalities and divergences over history, the type of collegiate body would certainly be the forum where the nature and state of social justice issues in a specific national polity are to be debated (SEP : Economics and Economic Justice, 2013). This would not be an exception in Korea. While Korea has practiced the constitutional democracy since 1948, NASK often had been less powerful or usurped, in some sense, below its expected role in the Republican democracy or liberal politics. This means that it has, most of times, generally be seen a feeble institution under the kind of charismatic presidents. From his personal background, Syng-man Rhee had been strong as a national leader of independence from the Japanese imperial rule. He had a hereditary affinity with the Chosen dynasty and one of most enlightened intellectuals educated in the US. Chung-hee Park also ruled in any absolute hierarchy beyond the congressional check and balance, which had been a root basis in his militaristic might and growing quest to national industrialization and economic development. Chun Doo-hwan, who had reigned during 1981-1988 and one of his protégé, would largely be disposed in some similar fashion, who ruled the country in his personified way. The constitutional institution and system were be neglected or disregarded, and the personal network prevailed. It is, however, interesting that the theme of social justice, in his period of rule, made a debut in the Korean politics, at least in the parlance of government owing to the enhanced status of national economy (2013). The role and performance of NASK, therefore, largely depends on the constitutional system and political culture in a specific country. In this respect, NASK, who could be considered as leveled with the western counterpart in its culture and performance, has truly begun since the 1987 constitutional reform and Roh Tae-woo’s administration. Two Ethical or Societal Issues The First Case For the purpose of illustration, let me pick up two issues which possess a different characteristics in terms of the classic liberty and nearer concept of social rights (Universal Declaration of Human Rights, 2013; Crocker, L.H., 1980; SEP: Positive and Negative Liberty, 2013). The first example, contended in view of the ethics or social justice, aroused a 89 public attention about the conflict of interest (Hicks, D., 2013). It poses the challenges, in an analogous context, concerning many issues and agendas of ethics and administration, such as Russian Mafia or Chinese trauma of corruption, although its substance involves a small ambit of national pension for the retired congressmen. Therefore, an ethical dilemma of the issue exhibits a good aspect of discussion about the liberty, equality and social justice, particularly from a perception about the ways of operation within the collegiate bodies (Cooper, T., 2012). The second example developed in the context of municipal program concerning the child subsidies. Seoul city, in the initiative to promote a political philosophy and social justice, has endeavored on the program, which now faces a difficulty from the worse national budget. The issue progressed contentiously and in any intensity of public controversy, which had both strands amenable to public criticism as well as progressive activism. It shows a fine context of political interplay, the concern of which spans over the roles and responsibilities between the national and local governments, as well as the political ideals both major parties engineer in continuance. A contention and disagreement on this issue had fueled a major debating point in the mayor election, and no candidate would be convinced of his unwavering probabilities about winning the election. This would go as same in the 2014 local election since the program also was not supported this year by the national budget. The Pension Program for the National Assemblyman in Korea (PPNAM) was pursued around 2009, and the statute has passed in Mar. 2010. Since 2013, an implantation was secured through the 2013 national budget approved by the national assembly. The official title of statute to ground the PPNAM is the Supportive Act of Democratic Constitutional Rule in the Republic of Korea (SADCRRK, 2013). The Act provides in its pertinent article, “the National and Local Government would grant the subsidies in the purpose to meet the cost and fund which are deemed necessary to support the operation of Democratic Constitutional Association and its senior members above the age of 65 (2013). To put it simply, the goals of statute has been intended to support the former and standing congressmen, who only could enter the Association and obtain its membership. So it has the nature of seniority pension program on the condition of its membership, which at least one chance of successful candidacy and qualification as a congressman is required. The Second Case Other ethical issue for the National Assembly involves the Free Fostering Plan of Child (FFCP), which has led to a serious public debate about the social justice and feasibility of that plan (AECFP, 2013). There had been factors to affect an implementation, for example, excessive budget or incidental irrationalities from the unrefined system (Cooper, T., 2012). Often it was put in contrast between the opposing party, Minjoo, and conservative ruling one, Saenuori. As the local election for a Seoul mayor profiles so high in view of Korean politics, the parties most always do their best to attract the voters and persuade on their strengths of public policy. Seoul citizens often are an educated intellectual who can assess the policy issues and their consequence, who are large to account for one fourth of national populace. Seoul is also the province of contention with a half to half cut leading to any decisive margin for key national elections, such as Presidential and National Assembly. The Plan particularly gets to be problematic since Seoul also is required to be responsible for many social programs including the Free Food Program for the Middle and High Schools and because of its pressing political gravity between the two parties (Korea JoongAng Daily, 2013). I now brief 90 on the feature of that programs, the issues and challenges, points of assessment as well as factors to affect an implementation of both Plans. Key Social Justice Themes The First Case The ethical dilemma of this program contributes to the worse public sentiment as it is problematic in view of the public conscience and reason (Chosun Daily, 2013). The kind of program was not unique in Korea, but a scope of developed countries enacted and implemented such policy. They generally are, however, considered as designed reasonably and in the permissible fashion. US, UK, Germany and France could come within this class, and Japan has recently abolished the system. PPNAMs in these countries mandate a stern classification about an eligibility to the pension money, and the sum was not fixed unlike Korea. It maintains, however, a sliding system on the calculation method which pertains to each specificity. Let me tender an extent of its flaws and weaknesses. First, the scope of eligibility is rather comprehensive and too generous to disable a prudent assessment about the merits. The Act provides ten disqualifying causes in this end, yet to be insufficient because of its ambiguities and catch-all dealings inoperable to exclude an impertinent beneficiary. The practical consequence of this flaw would be that the assemblymen can claim a monthly alimony if to serve a short of one year only. This contradicts a prevailing concept and social justice for which the national pension system is directed. Second, the system would be vile since it did not filter the context of other pension beneficiaries. This means that they may exploit a dual receipt of pension, which doubles their retirement income and causes a social injustice in terms of public welfare. Even for the unworkable scope, e.g., a retired wage assemblyman, the pension would purport to ensure a basic level of human subsistence without the labor. The ideals would be disserved or perverted by allowing the same or more compensation for whose labor cease. This multiplicity problem is now debated around many drafts of pension programs, for example, the National Pension Plan (NPP) and Basic Subsidies Program of Aged People (BSPAP). In the case at matter, the alimony is ten times bigger than BSPAP, and NPP requires a contribution from the beneficiaries. Hence, the dual or multiple eligibility obviously comes more serious in PPNAM. The alimony monies are rather gross in amount. According to the 2009 statistics from the National Pension Foundation, the spouses residing within Seoul are entitled to 1,100 and 1,008 dollars on a monthly basis since 2006, who contributed an installment during 219 months and 218 months respectively (Chosun Daily, 2013). This means that 18 years of contribution of statutory sum in each month could only qualify them to as less than 1,200 dollars. In comparison, an alimony for the retired congressmen, which is set at 1,200 dollars, outpaces it. One day service in the national assembly may bring a more economic benefit than the earnest and honest middle class of Korea. The NPP now undergoes a downward adjustment from the public pressure, but the alimony for them would be adjusted upward as corresponds with the price index. This leads to the challenges about the public sensibility of justice, equity and equality (SEP: Economics and Economic Justice, 2013; Cooper, T., 2012). The Second Case 91 In the second case, the Plan, around Mar. 2012, was designed to promote a social reproduction if the nation was in the face of radical decline within the birth rate. It was pursued by the national government without an exception and on no discriminatory basis. The government applied a scale to increase the subsidies amount, but it has made no significant effect on the parents since it was less effected (AECFP, 2013). The parents may commit their children in some time frame to the public facilities. Besides the subsidies, however, an additional expense falls within the responsibility of parents, such as that for the education or activities. More problematic would be a serious confusion and unpredictability in the floor of public facilities, which stems from the lack of standard, rules nor ethical guideline on the subsidies system (Korea JoongAng Daily, 2013). The system is entirely on the basis of financial contribution by the direct transfer of currency amount. This serves a distortion of system in an intense competition for cash, and undermined the public value of fostering service, the kind of utilitarianism, an expansion of public infrastructure, as well as a liaison or network concept in bridging the private and public for the maximization of happiness. A particular note on the increase of the Household Fostering Service would show a floating away of public commission and trust, but it merely expedited the private enterprises to exploit as their income source. A tremendous amount of budget actually made a lesser effect since the quality of service provision and cost management were neither officially nor institutionally controlled (Reichert, E., 2011). This factor baffles a more efficient outcome. The Plan also has a critical flaw which was failing to exercise a policy survey and assessment concerning the addressee’s class. This failure is a principal culprit for the abusive and imprudent vagary of clients, “file first and wait to see.” On this basis, the true addresses in need of public fostering service could get in a secondary priority or excluded eventually from the benefit of service. Major Challenges and Factors to Implement The First Case A problem of the first case lies in the fact that it contravenes a basic promise and frame of public pension system in that no installment was exchanged for the bargains of eligibility (Chosun Daily, 2013). This way of dealings is prevailing and basic on the kind of system, as we see in NPP, BSPAP, and National Pension System for Teachers, as well as one for governmental employees. This point comes central that most of the conscientious people expose their sentiment and get to be disgruntled. It aroused them that the social justice and equity was either in imbalance or undermined. Other problem lies in the vulnerable system of monitoring and feedback. As said, the exculpatory clause enters the scope on exemption or disqualification (SADCRRK, 2013). The causes are vast to pertain to the initial determination of eligibility. Nonetheless, the regular device to check a qualification needs to be strengthened. The chief of Association is able to ask a submission of evidence to support their continued status as a beneficiary. However, it would be needed of mandatory as a matter of law. Other more enhanced system to ensure a continued check-up for eligibility would be desired. The controversy about this system has not been just on the public, but surfaces as a one of hyperboles within the political parties themselves (Chosun Daily, 2013). The Budget and Audit Committee of National Assembly (BACNA) prepared the white paper, which includes a reaction and resilience of the people in concern and dissatisfaction. The critical 92 points in this paper would be same as briefed that the basis to pension benefit is stripped solely with the age requirement. The elements often factored as a standard in the public pension system, such as income, assets, an employment years, had been waived. That would transgress the ideals of frame instituted in other occupational pensions or National Pension. The controversy became especially serious since they are norm creators and receivers of norm. The ethical dilemma within the conflict of interest as well as prejudice on their position power and privileges enhanced a public contention and criticism (Hicks, D., 2013; Cooper, T., 2012). This aspect was geared up by the media and public press, which heralded an informed disclosure about the issue. A short service assemblyman and the criminals upon the termination of prison terms would not be excluded which could be sufficient to question its ethics and social justice (Laureate Education Inc. a, 2013). A dual or multiple receipt and too much alimony were also pointed out in the paper. One other critical flaw was illustrated that the system avoids an eye from the economic condition of national assembly man or his household. The Second Case We now turn to see the challenges and factors to affect an implementation of the second policy, which, amongst of all, could be encapsulated into three points of consideration. First, the budgetary constraints distort the Plan and lead to a complex ethical or social justice dilemma. On the last day, 2011, NASK approved an increased sum of budget from the governmental proposal covering the subsidies amount for the 0-2 years children (AECFP, 2013). This social benefit was fixed in a scheme over the years whose income ranges as lower than 70 percents. A scope of social welfare programs often have been pursued in a match with the local governments, which, as a corollary, require an incidental local budget in the process (Korea JoongAng Daily, 2013). As the Plan was released on public notice, new demand increased dramatically and the required budget amount doubled. The national conference of city majors and province governors forecast an increase from the 50 percent households to the point around 70-80 percents, who commit their baby for the care of Plan facilities (2013). The local governments, largely troubled on an unsound budget and often vulnerable in the state of financial independence, have to undertake the Plan by creating a heavy debt and owing to the absence of sufficient intergovernmental coordination in advance. Jong-bum Lee, who is a chief administrator of local governments, lamented, “The subsidies for the Plan would be drawn in the form of matching funds, and usually in the half to half ways between two governments en toto, which depends on a specific condition of respective local government. NASK miscalculated the number, 30 percents households disserved in the past, and expected 3.7 million dollars to meet the demand. The new demand unexpectedly exploded that the financial burden of local governments amounted to as high as 7 million dollars” (2013; Reichert, E. 2011). The National Planning and Financing Department and other agencies shared an expectation that the budget basis will be drained within about 10 to 17 local governments in June and July, 2012. One Seocho-gu officer said, “Seocho-gu would be most serious. Other adjacent prescient would be supported with 6o percents share from the central government, but ours would be as less as 30 percents. This means that we will have to discontinue in this June because of the financial unfeasibility” (2013) 93 One rank officer of local government also deplored, “The residue from the last year was officially transmitted to the local government in May. However, this monies already was planned to complement the shortage of NPPAP and other public projects. Then the monies would not serve any fiscal deficit from the FFCP. Any more drastic measure only could save the current dilemma of fiscal impasse” (2013). FFCP was designed and attempted absent any consonance and prior consultation with the local governments, and processed in the NASK. This anomaly from such unilateral initiative should be put on the shoulder of that responsible dimension, i.e., a central government. As the FFCP began to be implemented, over new five hundred public facilities had been recorded through only two months period, Dec, 2011 and Jan. 2012. Only 35 were national and public facilities, but other 438 private ones increased in number by twelve times to the former Plan (2013). This course of multiplication also went same in 2005 and 2006 provided that a subsides amount on the basis of facilities diminished as well as that on the children basis increased. We can chart a same mode of progress that the private or a free home fostering form multiplied, that a competition to induce the children intensified, while the pursuit of commercial interest swaying as unethical. The national or public facilities got marginalized in number as less in 5.3 percents, and the private facilities predominated a provision of service. The policy goals from the Plan had a central focus on the expansion of subsidies amount, and the increase of infrastructure or facilities was on the list in policy items, but set aside because of an insufficient budget. This critical flaw virtually paralyzed the Plan, and well calls upon its halt or suspension. A focal attention from the consumers of Plan would rather sees a trust and credibility related with the quality of facilities and adequate management or supervision. Given the burden from an additional expense, the Plan’s primary goal would less effectively work (Cooper, T., 2012). A use rate of fostering facilities for the 0-2 years children amounted to 50.5% in 2009, which allows a third spot in the OECD statistics. This rate is too high in factors from the OECD recommendation that 30% would be adequate and the home breeding would be a better option below the age two. Korea surpassed the recommended rate four years ago. Only Holland and Sweden outranked Korea by 83 and 66 percents respectively. Their case would be distinct that 72 and 76.5 percents of parents are working while Korea shows only 29.9 percents of parents on the employment status (Korea JoongAng Daily,2013). This statistics shows that no strong reason afforded a ground for such high rate of subscription to the public fostering service in Korea. This trend principally seems to be caused from the unsavory rush of parents, which perhaps would be from the intuition of free riding and any hallucination of loss. No genuine concern seems to be posited on the committing parents. This trend is certainly inimical to the most seriously interested households, say, working mother homes. The system legally misled a consumer’s classification by exclusively relying on the number of children for each facility, as well as the “first come first served” dealings. The housewife mother homes can petition earlier to frustrate a working mother. From the launch of Plan, their propensity got worse to consume the whole hours as maximum as possible and legally entitled to them (AECFP, 2013). 94 It is a postulate dominantly accepted that an affinity and pathos created around the earlier years of children as 24 months is determined to form a healthy psychological ego, i.e., social attitude, personal emotion, and trust relation in later years. A stable affinity and pathos in these years also affect to develop their brain or mental capacity, and autonomy as well as maturity of an ego later years. Otherwise the children would suffer a mental dip about an aggressiveness or brutal hostility and degradation of self-confidence or sense of trust. Any best way to increase the affinity and pathos of children is a mother’s hug that needs to be frequented, and some intimate contact with a biological mother. Ericson, an influential author in this area, particularly stressed the importance of early childhood and intimate relationship between the mother and child. Myoung-hee Ahn, a professor of psychology in the Seogang University, also adverted, “The mother plays a role to bridge the world and child in his or her earlier years. The children can develop the character and intuitive power to overcome a frustrating pressure or strains. A lack of this phase in earlier years often causes a self-suspect and distrust of the exterior world. Korean tradition once would be a paradigm that the western household worshipped to follow. That now is no realities here” (2013). A public employee, named Hye-jeong Choi, served five years to provide a fostering assistance and said, “She is discontent with the Plan. The children committed to her care, all through the daytime, are crying for her biological mother, and the apparent context of subsidies benefit usually incurs an impulse of non-working housewife to ask for long hours of care.” She now works in the Seoul Child Facilities, which operates from 7. 30 in the morning through 7. 30 in the evening.” A tax abuse and additional expense burdened on the parents also pose the challenges. Some of the fostering facilities enforced a wholesale increase of incidental expenses for 3-4 years children although they focused on the five-years group. This practice urges a follow-up investigation and adequate policy response at the national scale. The government granted subsidies in sum on the basis of law, and the facilities often should neither trade off that nor even increase the cost from other justification (AECFP, 2013). This could make a policy effect by never reducing the pocket expense of parents and because of the tremendous amount of budget, i.e., 1.2 billion dollars. Their basis to increase an incidental charge is ambiguous, such as the heating cost or event expense. Nonetheless, the local governments, a principal actor to supervise the system, have not performed any research nor initiate a supervisory command to ensure the transparent administration. This status, highly irresponsible and neither fiduciary nor ethical, forecloses the initial ambition of this plan, which would practically be obvious over ten private facilities at the urban Seoul (Cooper, T., 2012). The fostering administration often does not function in the public trust and credibility, which would likely be from the unethical and interest-driven owners. A short minute of care legally entitle them to claim the subsidies so that they often prefer a housewife children rather than those of working mother. It is highly selective that an easy access to the facilities was baffled. As the quota of children increased, the quality of service would degrade and a workload of fostering teachers gets tougher. The benefit ascribed to each party also shows 95 that the policy grossly favors the fostering facilities, which, in dollar amount, 800 for the facilities, 400 for parents, and 200 for the fostering teachers (Korea JoongAng Daily, 2013). Finally, a geographical disparity can undermine the equal justice of this policy varying with the quality of fostering teachers and their service provision. The government implements a guideline on the work frame in time, which is from 7 in the morning through 7 in the evening. If the work frame would change to extend, the paper work of fostering teachers would add making it a twelve hours cumbersome work. Their compensation might be halted in some cases, which also got worse depending on the fiscal state of each local government. The fostering teachers tend to leave a deprived region for the high income locales, which often are populated with the working mother houses. A reform alternative to improve the facilities is dispensed by the terminal officers or owners which undermines the sense of pride and personal decency. However, they do not have an effective means to raise their political voice. That is because the fostering teachers are not represented collectively unlike the owners of facilities. The unethical owners often see a headcount of children as their income source, and some fostering teachers are incompetent or uncommitted. This context could impact seriously to the disadvantage of children. For the children of 0- 2 years range, a shortage in the supply of teaching servants poses a greater challenge, particularly for the locales of province and in the agricultural area. In case of Chung-chung Province, the necessary fostering teachers would be around 7,000 from the whole quota, 600,000, while the practical force is 6,000 in number (2013). For this reason, the quota often was not satisfied from 80 percents and even lower as 6o percents in the agricultural area. Three children would be assigned to match one fostering teacher, but the context is not being implemented as schemed. One local employee of government urged, “a special policy response needs to be shaped. Otherwise, the ambitious plan may be accused of perpetrating a serious discriminatory consequence” (2013; Reichert, E., 2011). Thirteen facilities among fifteen in Young-dong failed to recruit a requisite number of fostering teachers. Some provinces enacted to reimburse a special compensation in some small sum, but likely effects less. Recommendations and Outcomes The First Case BACNA reported a policy suggestion to remedy the identified problems, which is encouraging and on progress. They perceived a controversy in competing policy goals, i.e., an integrity and sanctity of congressmen as a constitutional agency and the acceptable design of system. They are required of high standard of position ethics from the Constitution, statutes and internal ethical code, but the support of senior members, who could be economically deprived, is lacking. This context was responded, as said, by an enactment of the pertinent laws across the developed countries. Korea has already entered an advanced status, which requires exploring the needs of system more seriously. It increases a point of persuasion provided that the nation has long afforded an affluent public pension for the military personnel and government employees. BACNA adopted the alternative to go with the current system as is, while simultaneously launching the task force to be responsible for a revision. The revision project would begin with a collection of ideas and opinions from the incumbents and former national assemblymen. A first priority was suggested that the administration unit of NASK reviews the merit of sliding scale as well as the linking 96 possibilities with NPP (Chosun Daily, 2013). Their long term ideals would remain as same that it is required and ethically rewarding to support a financially vulnerable and aged assembly man. It comports with the requirement of social justice for their contribution and devotion to the nation. Therefore, their viewpoint on this agenda basically agreed on the fundaments of this system, but urged the need of political process for the popular support and sense of justice, as well as the equality and equity. The reform voice is not solely for BACNA, but the major political parties are active to modify the system toward a more reasonable one (Cooper, T., 2012). Three revision proposals are now pending and assigned with the responsible committee. This development would fall in a sharp contrast with the passage of Act in 2010, which was a one day process. The Second Case Most impending is that the policy makers have to be perspicacious in decreasing the quandary of policy abuse. How to be faithfully committed to the foster and care of children would be the way of fiduciary duty owed by public officials. A mere spending to grant and subsidize would vitiate the values on human right, liberty, as well as social justice (Laureate Education Inc. b, 2013; SEP : Positive and Negative Liberty, 2013; Universal Declaration of Human Rights, 2013). As surveyed, 0-2 years children would be more desired of home fostering, and many countries, in accordance with an OECD suggestion, institutionally support the mode of financial benefit. The Korean system, on the other, enforces a unitary scheme of public facilities, which can bring a discriminatory effect on the households. In consideration of the concerned parents and children, children over three years could be grouped for the fostering service. The national programs in this kind need to be designed carefully, which requires referring to the professional advice and adequate public forum. While we share the merit of subsidies in the cause of welfare expansion, the government will perform well if to revalue the scheme for home breeding of children below 2 years in age. The present system limited an access to the public subsidies for the second class in the government wealth classification code if the household opts for a home breeding. It has to be revised that all classes can choose without any disadvantage between the home breeding and use of public facilities. This would serve the equity interest and would comport with an OECD suggestion (Cooper, T., 2012). A serious assessment of ill effect in the prior year was not made. Until 2011, the subsidies were dispensed exclusively to the users of public facilities. In 2012, the revision rather extended the amount of subsidies and avoided an acid criticism about the discrimination of home breeding (AECFP, 2013). A view announced from the Seoul YMCA is echoing, “As the children under the age of two would be done better at home, and this being in accordance with the OECD guideline….The public service would pertain to the group of three to four years, which requires the system to be transformed from the subsidies to a national child alimony” (2013) It is fortunate that the Department of Health and Welfare (DHW) accepted this view to allow the parents of 0-2 years children an option between two ways of dealings. It would also serve the equality and convenience of system to provide the voucher system where the parents can use only in case of needs. A tax benefit needs to be afforded in the purpose to 97 boost a birth as well as to meet the fostering needs of women. A tax deduction on the educational expenses also would be helpful. On other basis, it would make a public good if the policy can shift to be founded on the disparate income frame and scaling system. The national or public nature of facilities would yield a fair and impartial administration in experiences, and the workplace facilities would be urgent to improve the system. According to the Nov. 2010 report from the government, it obliged the statutory size of firms to provide the workplace fostering facilities, but four of ten would not satisfy that requirement (2013). The government keeps their names confidential to avoid the public criticism. The Civil Society on the Justice of National Economy, one of most active pressure group in Korea, claimed its public disclosure in the last June, but the response has been inattentive in any short comment, “It would jeopardize the property rights of citizen.” This interaction simply shows a historic contention between the liberal and social state paradigm. In the statistics, 236 among the whole 576 classed into the scope of statute failed to meet a legal requirement, which includes a workplace with more than 500 employees at total or more than 300 female workers. In conditions as the safety issue or lack of space, they may alternatively bear the expense to foster the children or designate other exterior facilities. The above 236 firms neglect on these duties, and the aspect of penalty or disciplinary measure has to be reinforced relying on the requisite legal provisions (2013). Philosophies and Theories The cases described above show a typical dilemma about the classic ideas of government as well as the modern national paradigm in the pursuit of social justice or welfare. The first case can be ethically questionable if the lawmakers could enact a law to their self- interest. In the modern ethical term, the pension plan possesses a quality of contention possibly in derogation of the right ways on the conflict of interest requirement (Hicks, D., 2013). The legislative power is expected to operate under the separation of powers principle (SPP), hence, this traditional adage of legal principles can be reminded to respect. As incorporated into the Constitution, the standard as to regulate their conduct and ethics would approach as powerful as in the cases, such as the prohibition of ex-post laws or self- incrimination. Otherwise, even the natural law theory could also mandate to conform their conduct to the inviolable concept of justice. For example, it is self-evident that nobody can enact the laws for himself in any discriminatory or specific ways to dispose. The laws need to keep on the essence of justice in general as well as in the form of abstract terms or prescriptions. A classification and way of dealings are required to be impartial and unbiased so as not to disparage the intrinsic of executive power (Kranich, N., 2007). Hence, it is strictly forbidden to enact the kind of dispositive law, but the acts should allow an interpretive leeway expected to operate within the province of executive power. That assures, as a way of inter-branch check and balance, the ideal of separation of powers principle and against any arbitrary abuse of vested powers by one branch of government. The vehicle of SPP, hence, could enable a “division and loyalty” to the popular democracy. We often say the “divide and rule” axiom in the traditional operation of labor union and in the imperialistic ways of ruling for the subject states. The idea shares a similar attributes except that the public administrators have to be loyal to their sovereign and popular will. The public administrators are no longer placed to the role and responsibility on the successive or hereditary basis. They are elected by the people and may be appointed by the representatives of popular will. That is the only basis that they could be empowered and carry 98 their constitutional or statutory power. They are, in this respect, required to owe the kind of fiduciary duty and act on trust to serve the people in any faith, professional competence and capacity. As Cicero, a Roman philosopher on the ethics of ruler and social justice, said, “Justice is a fundamental element to be ensured of the rule or governance, which is only way leading to a human solidarity” (Laureate Education Inc. a, 2013). While the pension plan can fuel a controversy in light of the liberty and SPP, it also can evoke the dated notion of social justice and ethics of public administrators. Bentham perceived the importance of new thinking about a rule, its ideals, understandings, network, system, and organization. He offers a philosophical foundation for the modern positive state on the legislation and new covenant of public administration to share the revolutionary spirit (Audard, C., 1999; Postema, G. J., 2006). His utilitarian conception and theory could contest, in tenet and ethical requirement, the right ways which NASK had to opt for. His pursuit to maximize the individual happiness would be sublime for the administrators to bear in practicing their official duty. His free rider’s thesis is interesting which could well discourage this faithful public theorist. As outlined, the pension plan led to a high likelihood of public dissatisfaction and unhappiness about its sudden protrusion, hastened progress into the act, lack of public forum, insufficiency in provisions and inadequacy of finding an eligibility, as well as the high amount of subsidies. The goals and purpose triggered by the pension plan, however, could be verified to have a plausible ground. It was planned to support the great nationals who could not afford their lives in later years (Kranich, N., 2007). A fiscal feasibility is considered well in the purview of ordinate treasury and apparently costs less a burden. Many incidents developed in the NASK over the decade, however, proves in other way that several of such self-motivated measures frustrated the citizenry. The civil monitor group in Korea thankfully charted and reported to increase a public awareness. Notably, they have long years voted to increase their compensation under the circumstances where the national economy had staggered, the unemployment of youths disrupted the society, and the citizens were pressured so much to yield the highest rate of suicide in the OECD statistics. They often showed the tendency to side their peers in the incident of justice on the arrest of person, who ccould, then, claim his constitutional privileges and immunities as a national assembly man. They are never a housebreaker or highwayman whom Bentham made a wry wit about and who could stall the ethical and minded public administrators as saddened (Audard, C., 1999; Postema, G. J. (2006). They seem a due cause to institute the plan, which complies with the comparative illustrations of developed states. The practical aspect of Plan, as suggested, could be reexamined in the end to create a supportive ethos of people. FFPC was pursued in the social welfare sprit and in order to promote the birth rate of nation. The social justice and equity, however, would posit a serious challenge as we detailed above. It does neither involve the conflict of interest nor ethics of congressmen in any conspicuous dress, but the redistribution of resources and wealth could possibly be misdirected or in the vein of structural or implementation flaws (Hicks, D., 2013). Most problematic is the present context of progress that a true beneficiary could be discriminated in the interest of facility owners leading to an ineffective consequence and contravening the intended goal of service. The equity, most closely related with the whole scale of social justice, would not be operated as deviated from the expected trajectory of Plan. The housewives have grown in number to exploit the benefit of plan as a primary class of beneficiary so that the working mother home, a target class of the Plan, was set to be secondary since the committed care requires a more hours and work demand. From the libertarian view in clanning on the original freedom and property right, the welfare expense 99 in this type would not be supported. They would entertain their ground that no legitimate basis to spend the tax income and public funds without any key public use, such as police and national defense service. The positive liberty concept, however, suggests its role more affirmatively that the working mothers can be enabled to exercise their function and liberty with the welfare assistance (Crocker, L.H., 1980; SEP : Positive and Negative Liberty, 2013). They can work thanks to the public aids, and can manifest their capabilities, talents, and economic activity in freedom. The negative liberty or equal opportunity from the least involvement or less regulation of state could not reach this dimension. The context of controversy also reveals an equality concern that the functional equality, implored by Dworkin and Sen, could be served if to be compared between the working mothers and unmarried maiden (2013). The government made a classification to serve their policy goals in the benefit of household, which has the intended range of children, i.e., 0-3 years old. This brings the consequence of unequal treatment among the citizens, which can possibly abridge the equality of resources and opportunity. The first principle, in the Rawls proposition, can see its way to the complex equality for the aids and grants to restore a justice. The veil of ignorance in the Rawlsian understanding could be posited about the deprived and child burdened household incidental to the working mothers. They are economically vulnerable, but could contribute to the increase of birth rate and national production or economy. The idea or concept can be shared in the same strand when the developed countries boost the developing counterparts by aids and grants, which Rawls and the current structure of WTO espoused as their economic justice (SEP: Economics and Economic Justice, 2013). The context of interplay would upgrade the function of them and contribute to the material welfare of humankind as well as the increase of world economy. This scheme on social justice would be perceived as ambition-sensitive as Dworkin focused. A retreat to merely an endowment- sensitive approach of equality would lead an intolerable waste of working force and huge sojourn of human resources. The equity or equality requirement may be highlighted by pointing to the geographical terms of nation. A fiscally deprived local governments may suffer a minimal operation of fostering facilities which marginalized the service in a specific region. This would incur a great potential to deprave the legitimacy of Plan, so that the government is required to elicit the standard and revised scheme. It could be on feedback from the initial implementation period of Plan. The supervision and monitoring process need to be enhanced and be controlled to remove the chance of owner’s unethical or contradictory commitment. The nursing teachers would be a precious actor to perfect the Plan. The government should prevent an intermediary exploitation of owners or managers of facility, increase and maintain the quality and faith, and procure a requisite number of teachers to fulfill the demand. Concluding Insights About the Ethics and Responsible Administration of Collegiate Body The rapid context of globalization and geographical compression may be enabled by the technological advancement in the new millennium. I believe that this factor transformed the mode of governance where the collegiate body would penetrate the differing polities on the universal basis (Cooper, T., 2012). Now the people, or global public at this time, perhaps 100 would be less attracted by the political or economic theories, which have depraved the polities to their own way. The Orient and West also had long been deemed heteronomous between the western liberals and communists or feudal Orientalism. The impact of e- technology, as a most notable influence, now affords the opportunity to share and sense in any common attributes of humanity or society. Now the ethics or social justice, which is, in many subtleties, intimate, delicate, and applied beyond the established formality of western intelligence, can appeal not only in the national politics but also in the international plane (Laureate Education Inc. a, 2013). We can encounter a usual scene of summit meetings who exchange their personal value, perception and administrative ethics. That would often not be the case when we consider the most universal body, i.e., national assembly or congress. An interchange in this domain may be in the network or liaison, but could not be leveled to the context of summit. Particularly, the way of executing their constitutional duties would be rather different as pointed out. For example, anonymity in their vote could render them even less responsible than even the executive officials. The two issues discussed above expose a very basic contrast across the self-enactment, self-interest, social welfare and justice, positive liberty, as well as the human rights to a decent condition (Donnelly, J., 2013; SEP: Human Rights, 2013; Universal Declaration of Human Rights, 2013). The first case involves a classic notion concerning the potential power abuse as coupled with the social welfare of target group. The second case deals with some most enhanced science and reasonableness of the social welfare program. Both issues actually sensitized the Korean people in a great concern and interest than any other serious economic issues. This implies that the netizenry and people in this new millennium are largely disposed to track intimately on the public administrators who long enjoyed an insulation and independent nobility. The trend may go similar in the socialist elitism of Congress or communist parties, and converge to be subject to the public monitor or critical eyes. However, the ethics of them were not dealt in any coherent manner which factors the attributes as a collegiate body. I suggest that the Cooper’s model may serve an individual member of collegiate body at this point of time, and hopefully expects for further studies more suited to the ethics of collegiate body (Cooper, T., 2012). Both issues actually disclose a square aspect of ethical failure to pull down the public image of NASK. Behind the controversy and public disappointment, we regret if they might neglect on a due regard to the required ethics. This could have been ameliorated if he or she individually and seriously assessed the problem on the kind of Cooper’s deliberation. The attributes and qualities of organization also seems to matter in the kind of “institutional inertia” or amok, which requires a system studies of ethics and public administration concerning the collegiate body (2012). The ethics and social justice are one of sensitive topic for the contemporary administrators and global public. For the material conditions have improved, this theme poses an aspect of serious challenges to attract our attention. The contemporary literature in this field had been dealt mostly with some philosophical studies, practical point of public administration, and some of efforts on theorization or design approach. The outcome of this less exposure and unattended research would lead to the lack of pertinent frame to analyze more systemically and in affluent sources of reference for the different nature of public organizations. While Cooper’s ethical decision making model shows some of mental stages to deliberate on the ethical dilemma and challenges, it could possibly possess a universal quality as the design of ethical decision making process (2012). However, it is highly generalized to neglect on the specific nature of public organizations. I would like to withhold 101 looking into the private or for profit organizations since the theory or metaphor with the public ones would properly subdue their minimal nature of dealings. Given the Cooper’s analysis and approach provides a good model in the aspect of formality and mental progress about the specific public administrators, it is also necessary to substantiate the quality of ethics or social justice issue in terms of the attributes of public organization (2012). In this standpoint of view, I intend to make a distinction between the bureaucratic nature and collegiate body of public organizations. There are a scope of public organizations in the different nature, which maintains a bureaucratic work structure, notably the executive branch of government, foundations, and high supported charity organizations, public schools, and so. There could we find the collegiate form of organizations, such as congress or national assembly, public commission or council, consortium on the public project, and etc. The quality and attributes concerning the interplay of ethics or social justice with the collegiate bodies could be clarified in several aspects against the bureaucratic types. First, the organizational members generally would enjoy an equal status and competence that a complicated or aura of ethical issues distinctly arising from the context of command and obedience would not be present. Second, the organizational members often undertake an important role and positional power as a decisional body, which would be to leverage their ethical requirement more stern in some cases, but more softened in other cases. Both cases discussed above could be viewed in the latter light. Third, they would be a norm or standard giver and simultaneously a norm or standard receiver, who has to respect the ethics codified or required in any form. They could be plenary to regulate their conduct, but the tradition and social attention would monitor as coupled with their good conscience and personal quality or integrity (Maccallum, G.C., 1993). The specific context of norm formulation, for example, anonymity in the vote, could have a potential to be resilient in producing a socially desirable ethical code. In some of response, we may reinforce a stricter scheme about the name-designated enactment, open vote to be name-disclosed, and the kind of intensive hearing sessions about the sensitive social welfare program as well as a public forum indispensable with the agenda on conflict of interest, and etc. Fourth, they perform their job responsibility on the ad hoc basis in many chances that the ethical requirements would normally be less serious nor challenging than the employees in bureaucracy. Therefore, I consider that the standing status of organization would be more a factor in distinction. For example, the panel would be a lower and ad hoc basis arrangement while the appellate body staffed with tenured judges within the standing nature would be seen otherwise in the context of WTO. Fifth, it seems also relevant about the ways of ethical process whether the organization is governmental or entitled to the constitutional privilege. The non- governmental organizations of public nature would share the attributes in middle status between the private and governmental branches. Given the constitutional privileges, the national assembly, for example, would face a distinct body of ethical practice on the tradition and constitutional expectation. For example, it could be a virtue for them to more readily disclose a public truth in the Floor, which is other than the ranked bureaucrats or executive 102 directors. The philie buster could also be viewed not strictly unethical, although we see it undesirable in some cases. Other governmental organizations, however and across the jurisdictions, tend to be governed uniformly by the centralized statutes or decrees on the ethics and responsibility as a public officer (Laureate Education Inc. a, 2013). From the Econo-political (West) to Ethics or Justice Discourse (Orient and West) The two cases exhibit the typology of western thoughts between the liberal and social dualism projected over the scope of disciplines, i.e., politics, economics, sociology, law, and so (Murphy, A., 1998). The cases also exhibit typical burdens which the public administrators, over the long centuries or decades have been posed as challenges. The two cases would perhaps be irrelevant with the locus of nations, if to be west and east. For example, the spoils of victory in 19 th America would still be on vestige and ethically challenged by some of public views. The Russia Mafia or Princelings in China over the decades would also show a dilemma involving the conflict of interest in any grand scale. The social welfare policy also could be shared in the communist states, and China notably intensifies the liberalization of national economy within the socialist basics (Hunt, L., 2008). They may restructure a perfect, but minimally afforded social welfare due to the materialistic incapacity. The liberal western states also struggle with any adequate extent of social welfare policy. Hence, the two cases are prone to seriate the wake of history and hemisphere on earth, which drove us to mediate on the practical and ethical aspect of academic thinking. I consider the ethics and responsible administration studies in prongs, possibly with sharing and reaching the common breath between the West and Orient, as well as the communists and liberals. The traditional frame is dominantly western, hence, econo-political to implant. Now I consider, however, that the needs or background on this intellectual exposure could be said a tradition or basic, mere a backdrop or in the least practically not arguable. We may impeach an evil state on human rights violation, but never condemn them as they are a communist regime of national economy or so (SEP: Human rights, 2013). Notwithstanding the famous word, “demise of ideology,” we now generally agree on its flip side, but some of new trends in our everyday lives. Reverting to the cases, we suppose that the rulers in power should be on some ethics about the conflict of interest, and that the social welfare program could lead to the positive liberty or functional equality and the kind of substantive justice (Laureate Education Inc. b, 2013; SEP : Positive and Negative Liberty, 2013). Often the econo-political frames have been imposing to structure our intelligence, but the massive society or close context of public interaction on e-technology or for other many reasons, now defines the practical points of contention in other ways. While neither or only minimal improvement could be ascertained from the earlier century or decades of Congress in both issues, the public now are more interested in their ethics, manner, motives of policy, and the kind of justice attitudes. The contemporary society poses a multifaceted challenge of human condition and lives in dignity (Hunt, L., 2008). A progenemonon to the modern civilian society enabled a materialistic prosperity in our living conditions although some of awakened voice claims an aspect of fundamental wrongs from the generalization and consequent amok from the unbeknownst or intoxicated leverage of massive general base or manageable citizens. They have a concern about the unemployment rate, stalemate of economy not to satisfy the population growth, as well as their income or retirement prospect in terms of the assets or pension. The modern structure of politics and economy has settled well making them to be a merely adaptive 103 personality and to focus on their chores vastly. This constant tone and ethos in the lives of dominant class would be refreshed by an occasional exposure to the international controversies or idiosyncrasy from the politics and national or international leaders or other exotic experiences. However, that would not entail a serious political or economic issue to disrupt their pleasant personal domain (Murphy, A., 1998). If we now gradually acknowledge G2 politics and the rise of Oriental power, we may be helped with some of useful insights from the standing Chinese leaders. In the hierarchy and rank order, the newspaper introduced three Chinese leaders, Xi jin Ping, Lee, and Hwang. The leaders had addressed his interest by illustrating a most influential book in his respective leadership. Xi, as matched with his top national status, illustrated a Chinese novel titled Ordeals and New Plane and authored by the professor of Chinese Military Academy. Lee, as a second rank of leadership, was concerned about the national economy, and mentioned the book which frontiers the second industrialization on the fossil fuels toward the third of information technology (1998). Hwang shed a light on the insights and wisdom proposed by A. Tocqueville about the revolutionary social condition. China, besides his rising status in the world economy, is a most populated country. We now witness that the world becomes compressed to see a gradual congruence between the West and East or Orient for many reasons, for example, e-technology or some of decades experience of the liberal or social democracy. The civilian wake of democratic governance has trained both pans to share a common ground and openness to exchange. Despite a continued difference or contention at some extent, I like to suggest the ethics and social justice issue could be one of governing theme which the contemporary global public implicitly receives more than any other political or economic discourse (Laureate Education Inc. b, 2013). While, in the Lee’s interest, his book can bear an intellectual insight and serve to cultivate the mindset or attitude of national leaders, it may be seen to the large public as some of applied restructuring of the current structure within the global or national economy. For Xi, the Chinese novel would offer the soil and implied value or social compassion for this long history of grand nation, but might be nationalistic well to rebut a common rationale for the global public. It would come little to influence that it perhaps lacks a quality of socialism advocacy if the book is merely a novel other than any social science or professional books. Hwang’s regard to the Tocqueville’s may contain a universal theory or viewpoint about the revolution and social condition. However, it could be limited to the worse political condition of China for the still lower per capita income, gradual economic disparity between the poor and rich, and their prevailing adherence with the economic equality on socialism. If we turn our attention to the western mode of developed countries, the econo- political framework devoted to the western industrialization perhaps would exhaust its all the genesis in stalemate. Nobody questions the precious idea of free market and financial policy to energize the national or international economy. FRB has tried their best through the decades to vibrate the national and global economy, and the IMF as well as the World Bank could gladly take a part to cooperate and collaborate. We, the global public, however, could share merely in reticence, accomplice, nodding or support, and general credence of their wisdom and theory. This attitude or intellectual perception would also be same about the modern prevailing political discourse. Now the Korean people generally do not think if any swift of governmental structure to the parliamentary system would bring any difference on the politics or their actual ways of living. They probably would be correct to know if the scheme is keenly related with the turn of modern democracy from the feudal system. The 104 context would be said similarly as the second and third generation narratives in the economic transformation. So I believe that the contemporary global public, in the mid of post modern realities and besides some of distinct groups or individuals, would be vastly concerned of the ethics, social justice or responsible administration than the insipid reiteration of the property and freedom of contract generalization. An assembly man Choi, who is a floor leader of the National Assembly from Sanouri said, “Korea is now on excessive democracy than its lacking or insufficiency, in response with the street demonstration of opposing party.” This comment suggests some of truths that Korean public would detest a stereotype of political narrative on the democracy and freedom, demand a professional ethics, and is more sensitive to the social justice, and pays a due regard to the responsibility of public administrators. Lee Kuan Yew, a respected charisma of Singapore, impressively addressed the Oriental virtues as distinct and precious through the long history (Postema, G. J., 2006). Eo-ryung Lee, a distinguished professor from the Ewha Woman’s University in South Korea, also emphasized thorough his brilliant academic career the Korea and Oriental philosophy, the strengths of Oriental values, and predicted a new cultural primacy of Orient in the new millennium. He commented, “The first millennium had been an era of Oriental dominance in the material prosperity and cultural superiority.” The second thousand years had been led by the Western power to embed the democracy and idea of free market in the world. The new millennium would be wheeled ahead by the Oriental influence where the ethics and values in the esoteric nature could be shared and expand into the universalized respect and followership (2006). For the importance of China, I like to revisit an above illustration pointing out that they imply their social minds except as basically variegated with their urgent needs to administer their state developmental paradigm. Among the aspects of principle, I assess that they sacrifice the liberty interest in trade-offs with the equality adherence. The social justice and conception of human rights would compete, but would probably find a point of compromise with the western concept given the near future on any sufficient material conditions (Donnelly, J., 2013). It also complies with their state foundation recently conformed (SEP: Human rights, 2013). That briefed, I suppose that the future academics would deserve a new enhanced focus on the studies of ethics, social justice and responsibility of public administrators than any other times. 105 Reference A Harsh Response from the Citizenry Against the Passage of Alimony Act (2013, Jan. 6) Chosun Daily, Seoul, South Korea Act on Early Childhood Fostering Program (AECFP), Korea Stat 12068 (2013). Audard, C. (1999). Anthologie historique et critique de l'utilitarisme, tome 1 : Bentham et ses précurseurs (1711-1832). Paris: Presses Universitaires de France – PUF. Cooper, T. (2012). The Responsible Administrator. San Francisco, CA: John Wiley & Sons. Crocker, L.H. (1980). Positive Liberty: An Essay in Normative Political Philosophy (Melbourne International Philosophy Series), New York, NY: Springer. Donnelly, J. (2013). Universal Human Rights in Theory and Practice, Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Hicks, D. (2013). Dignity: Its Essential Role in Resolving Conflict, New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Hunt, L. (2008). Inventing Human Rights : A History, New York/London :W.W. Norton & Company. Kranich, N. (2007). Equality and equity of access: What's the difference? Retrieved July 10, 2008 from the American Library Association Web site: Laureate Education Inc. a, (2013). Ethics and Social Justice "Equality and Equity: Applications" with Amanda Baker (approximately 6 minutes) Laureate Education Inc. b (2013). Ethics and Social Justice "Liberty: Applications" with Amanda Baker (approximately 7 minutes). Local Governments on the National Child Fostering Program (2013. June 19), Korea JoongAng Daily, Seoul, South Korea. Maccallum, G.C. (1993). Legislative Intent/Essays, Madison. WI: University of Wisconsin Press. Murphy, A. (1998). Reason, Reality, and Speculative Philosophy. Madison WI: University of Wisconsin Press (1996). Postema, G. J. (2006). Interests, universal and particular: Bentham's utilitarian theory of value. Utilitas, 18(2), 109-133. Reichert, E. (2011). Social Work and Human Rights: A Foundation for Policy and Practice, New York, NY: Columbia University Press. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy : Economics and Economic Justice, Retrieved Nov. 2. 2013 from http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2008/entries/economic-justice/. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2008/entries/economic-justice/ 106 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Human Rights, Retrieved Nov. 2, 2013 from http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rights-human/. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy : Positive and Negative liberty, Retrieved Oct. 25, 2013 from http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rights-human/. Supportive Act of Democratic Constitutional Rule in the Republic of Korea (SADCRRK). Korea Stat 12068 (2013). Universal Declaration of Human Rights, Retrieved Oct. 3, 2013 from http://www.ohchr.org/EN/UDHR/Documents/UDHR_Translations/eng.pdf. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rights-human/ http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rights-human/ http://www.ohchr.org/EN/UDHR/Documents/UDHR_Translations/eng.pdf 107 XVII. Ethics of Workplace and Entrepreneurship The Current State of Ethics within the Workplace Nobody would disagree if the contemporary society is on the basis of professionalism and organizational lives (Ethics Resource Center, 2013)). Most of post- modern citizens, probably on the mid-income status, would be amok of the smacks of bureaucracy and their occupational activities. This group often constitutes the prevailing ethos of society and vertebrate of citizenry. They often are ascribed, in most of paradigm, as sovereign people and pillar of national politics or economy, who are the center of contest that the national morals and conscience would reflex and abound around. They are any standard of political or economic issues with which the political leaders have to interact. Their predominant disposition would be embedded on the organizational lives. I consider that three of simple principles would govern their professional course of dealings and commitment, which are ethics, political responsiveness, and merit (Yeager, S. J., Hildreth, W. B., Miller, G. J., & Rabin, J., 2007). These elements are actually overwhelming and powerful on which the leaders and followers could rely. The elements could be on a varying extent in response with the types, size, structure and culture of organizations. For example, the political branch would require more of political responsiveness than an ethics while the private organizations often consider it more important a merit than the former two. The quality of each element also could not be the same where the international organizations often are based on the more universal and loose, but grand principle of ethics than the national ones. The latter could be more enriched in substance and comes in an intense interplay with the leaders and organizational members. In many cases, a condensed, definite-to- pursue, disciplinary and integral, but even nasty on the chances of corruption or static pleasure as in the kind of bureaucratic mazes would the ethics of national organizations be. We often are less experienced of the corruption from the officers of international government. A former IMF chair person, S. Kahn, would come as one example, but we generally do not see it any serious ethical violation. The national aspect would go otherwise if we would consume some time on the news paper articles or reports. The current state of ethics in the workplace, therefore, would hardly be simplified in any single paradigm of assessment, but requires a case by case investigation by the supervisors and researchers (Ethics Resource Center, 2013). It is, however, obvious that the three elements would fairly assist in gauging the current state of workplace ethics. The diversity could come as a fourth factor leading to define the ethics state of workplace, and related with the multiculturalism in leading and managing. This triadic would, of course, need to be substantiated from the inculcation of public value, organizational mission and goals, as well as the political or societal virtues. It would be dissimilar of ethics, no matter if it may be societal and even organizational, between the socialists and liberalists, although it can be sublimated, particularly within this rapidly advanced and compressed global village, into any congruence or sharing of basic human attributes. Conceptually, three elements are independent to lead our organizational lives, but the ethics could be comprehensive to define and matter with other two. The merit, which would be ultimate in any utilitarian perspectives, can plainly impact the shape of ethics. Consider if 108 the bottom line of meritless employees or organizational policy would generally be deemed unethical or unacceptable. The political responsiveness is one criterion to influence the ways of response to some specific challenges. It could be virtuous in some circumstances, and may, in other context, fail of organizational or employee’s reputation or right ways that the organization are obliged to do (Yeager, S. J. et al., 2007). The whistle blowing may simply reveals this aspect of ethical conduct. This type of employees’conduct can well raise a serious debate about the ethics. Hence, the ethics could conceptually be extensive to cover all the three, and the issues have to be what scope of due play needs to be ensured in a specific organization about three different factors. A KPO Issue about the Organizational Ethics A Development of KPO Issue Recently, Seok-yeoll Yoon, a branch head of prosecution office in Korea (KPO), was assigned an important duty to investigate a grave political criminal case involving the central intelligence agency (KCIA). His skills and expertise were bought by the chief of KPO, and called upon to work in the special team of investigation. He was committed and faithful officer to emphasize a neutrality and sanctity within the national exercise of criminal authority. A sinister officer, in his view, has to be punished in proportion with his culpable conduct, no matter who they are. That is principled and authoritative in the prescription of supreme law of nation, and must have fairly been cautioned by himself about any exterior influence. He, in ranks and team structure, is responsible to Yeong-gon,Cho, who is his senior prosecutor and may assume a mediating role between the investigation and higher ranks of political propensity. The case entails a sensitive issue about the legitimacy of last presidential election, and was disputed about an allegedly impermissible engagement to draw the support for the candidate of ruling party. During the course of his professional activities, he might not obtain a favor from Y.G., Cho about his suggestion to tackle more extensively into the core of a nasty or undue influence from KCIA. Not clear in public relations, the context might be led to drop a positive alternative, and eventually exploded with a sudden public announcement of S.Y. Yoon about the unethical command or implied oppression to frustrate the ambition of this junior prosecutor. They were called upon the investigatory hearing held in the national assembly, and a serious inquiry or defense had been exchanged among the congressmen and two prosecutors. The opposing party, Minjoo, likely saw the incident challenging and opportunistic to strip off the ethics of Sanouri and current administration. Y.G. Cho, as a supervisor of special investigation team would be a right person to encourage his subsidiaries as suggested by Yeager, S.J. (2007). He seems to abandon his role to ensure the criminal justice of nation, and merely said,“I alleged him to be neutral or reticent, but in no intention to influence the key investigators in responsibility.” For its social impact and worse public sensibilities, the department of justice (DOJ) began to exercise a supervision authority to impugn and discipline if any misconduct would be confirmed. About two weeks ago, S.K. Yoon was rendered to divest of his official power and status, and Y.G. Cho shortly thereafter announced his resignation. Reflections The episode briefed above brings a point of reflections on the current state of ethics in KPO, and concerning the general aspect of organizational essences, job satisfaction, ethical 109 perspectives, external and internal ethics pressure, likelihood of changing jobs, and so on. The context is esoteric involving the twilight strands of organization, say, quasi-judicial and intra-executive qualities. The criminal justice system on this concern would get diverse, but the Korean system may be generic or dominant. In some of national system, notably in France, the prosecution offices operate within the judicial preserve, and they need to officially report to the court with regard to the administration and supervision. In the socialist states, the prosecution authority is considered to execute the will of people collectively, hence, sees less chances to be reflexive about the individual or professional conscience and theory of humanly justice. The political primacy is absolute which profiles ahead of traditional concept concerning the proportionality principle or perhaps a common understanding of western concept of distributive justice (Laureate Education Inc., 2008). KPO would possess dual qualities so that the administration were integrated into the executive, but shielded from the political influence by affording an independent statutory term of KPO’s chief officer. It also is severed from the command line, i.e., head of DOJ, for the specifics of criminal investigation. It is wiser since the resources are fairly required to meet such great number of criminal cases in personnel and apparatus. The executive, as we are aware, are the sources to administer the public policy with a vaster resource than the legislature or judiciary. The quasi-judicial nature of criminal investigation also requires an independent ground from the executive, which offers the ground to create the current system on the national statute and decrees. For the special matters of politics or other sensitive cases, the statute also provides an independent counsel to be appointed by and responsible to the congress, who is not a full- time public prosecutor, but lawyers, who often are experienced in rich career or retired rank officers. The independent counsel supplements to ensure the sanctity of criminal justice, and the system followed the American model as we see in the Star case for the former president, Clinton, as well as for the Watergate investigation. As the nature of society is highly professional and based on the experts from years of study and apprentice, the ethics in KPO expected to exercise often would not diverge, but be coherent in the same tone or manner of response (Frederickson, H. G., 1999). That, however, would not always the case as we also expect. This kind of sensitive issues particularly could be suspected of whether it would be disposed in comport with the public sense of justice and the ideals of criminal justice system. The case was fairly exciting to impress some quandary of ranked officers, and the research from Yeager S.J. could be applied in terms of importance we can find in the supervision role (Yeager, S. J. et al., 2007). The encouragement of supervisor, C.K. Cho in this case, could have a high potential to increase, even forefront the ethical perspectives of S.Y. Yoon. It would be an easier case for him technically, but entails a delicate aspect of national politics. Hence, a senior supervisor’s role seems determinative, but could be escalated by discussion, consultation, and intimate collaboration. The kind of interplay between the external and internal ethics pressure could come fancied that the former would, in high probabilities, be enormous and demanding. Of course, the young society of public prosecutors in Korea, like the judiciary, had been active and is committed to advocate the professional ethics as central. But the bureaucratic maze in KPO can effectively screen its influence or unacceptable suggestion. They have been a source of intra-organization flak on the public criticism and misconduct of the KPO higher ranks. But it would often be post- incident voice in the remedial recourse and in the end to restore their pride or public relations. Therefore, the external ethics pressure other than the young society must have been rather pounding so that supervisor’s role seems essential to shield and encourage. An unidentified miscarriage within the team or confidential interplay seems to have increased the ethics stress 110 for S.Y. Yoon, who eventually behaved like a whistle blower (2007). Someone may accuse him of committing the kind of vagary and others perceive him as conscientious or loyal to his job demands. We can confirm that the communication is really a critical factor working to maintain an organizational integrity and uniform fashion to proceed. We may well reserve other elements, say, job satisfaction or employee job attitudes since, in this case, they have eventually been depraved on their professional path. They would feel hard pains, and even the likelihood of changing jobs should not be excluded (2007). This incident has to be borne seriously in the mindset of or ethical guides for the posterity generation of prosecutors. I mean that the feedback should be adequate to teach and learn about how much the supervisor’s role would be important for the reputation and credibility of public organizations. The Ethical Management and Entrepreneurship In this discussion, I like to survey the corporations of Korea about its ethical management, its current status within the Korean context, as well as one of great illustrations in view of the management ethics and its social impact. How do we connote the concept of ethical management. In the dictionary, it is defined that the enterprises are required to be responsible to the social expectations beyond the management and legal accountability. The concept demands the increase of moral quality and profile of enterprises and encompasses a set of moral conducts and anti-corruptive deals between the employees and counterparts in trade, bribery in trade, as well as support of cultural or social events, givings and charity activities in the contribution to the society as a whole. The theme of ethical management was supported by an increasing number of enterprises according to the statistics of Korean Management Association (KMA) in 2005 (Ethics Resource Center, 2013). Over ninety percents of largest businesses in Korea have adopted an ethics charter. These enterprises also enacted a scope of ethics programs and action plans to be implemented in their work place. To illustrate some, KTF daily aired the ethics education drama through its intra-firm network since Mar. 2005. Shinsekae developed the ethics index to address the challenges. Posco also began to implement the reward system for the reporting of an unethical conduct. YK had obliterated some nasty strands of salary which were designated as marriage, funeral and public relations expense. LG electronics has continued to offer an ethics education program since Feb. 1994, the year of ethics declaration. KMA conducted a public survey addressed to the member companies and KOSDAQ firms, which are five hundred and completed in 2004. The positive response about the need of ethical management ranged at 38 percents. Same survey conducted in 1999 was as low as 6.8 percents. In the 1992 survey, the reason for ethical management was reported to lie in the social responsibility of enterprises, which accounted for 92.2 percents (Frederickson, H. G., 1999). This rate declined to the point of 60 percents in 2004. This indicates that the increasing profile of ethical management could arise in the concern of profitability other than social responsibility or public opinion. The Ethical Commitment of Yuhan-Kimberly and Its Impact on the Entrepreneurship & Social Change Yuhan-Kimberly is one of corporations which produces the consumer goods for home use (Sung, S.Y. & Choi, J.N., 2010). It attained an international acclaim which made a 111 top ten list in the survey of Asian Wall Street Journal in 2003. The survey ranked 900 Asian companies in terms of worker-friendly firm environment. The market share and recognition of YK products were superior than any other firms, which would well be benchmarked as a world class quality. The national economy these years were staggering. The unemployed youths amount to 500,000 in number and the red credit poor also radically increased to the number of 4,000,000. The domestic market has been in deep stalemate. Under these crises, one enterprise, named YK, has a remarked success in 4 times of sales increase as well as 17 times of net profit between 1991 and 2005. All of its eight sectors of business have entertained a top share in the market. This company was created in the partnership with Kimberly Clark, a US corporation and YuhanLtd., a Korean corporation in 1970 (2010). The Korean public were pleased to witness its success. It fairly deserves a public attention since the IMF crisis in the late 1990’s and economic diminution afterwards had made no factors without any layoffs nor radical rationalization of business. In the survey conducted 2003, it was ranked sixth by being highly rated in the job satisfaction, trust of employees on management, and social change factors. Then what strands enabled YK to continue on its prosperity? Is this a guaranteed bank note to be applicable for many other businesses? Is it easier to benchmark the success story to implant its modality in other firms? We may ascribe its esoteric nature of corporate culture to its splendor of success. I consider it one of successful paragon in any glocalizedculturalism. First, the top management pursued in continuance and conviction that the employment realtions will make better to be stuck on the Korean mode of livings, i.e., four days weekly for personal pleasure and leisure (2010). It is certainly ethical to increase the merit of employees in the workplace. It is contrary to the general theme about management, say, as possible as low pay and much extent of work hours. It would be paradoxical and eventually proved effective in eliminating the low rate of factory operation, increase of inventory, and disgruntled labor union. Its strategic , but ethical aspect of decision can be epitomized in two prongs, i.e., four frames of work turn and lifetime learning. The workers in the production line are divided into four turns. In this frame, they work four days and get off the duty also for four days. The free days will be consumed to develop a personal amenities and learning for self-improvement. This way to deal can effect on the increase of productivity for the employer and job stability for the employees. This management strategy is ethical to bring a merit, social justice, and positive liberty of employees. It also contributed to the social change in the corporate culture of Korea, and serves the national economy as a paradigm of Korean entrepreneurship (2010). It is impounding to make the turn toward a congruence, harmony and coexistence, human value and pain sharing of worse economic conditions. YK actually offered the model in the end to increase the trust, reliability and consensus among the family, individual workers, and company. The understanding was serious in holding a human value and its employment status, and they preferred a sharing on employment other than layoffs. Second, YK management also advanced to propel a competition of ideas from the employees and friendly interchange between them and labor (2010). This requires that the management should be committed ethically to interact and cooperate, and also based on the social attitudes distinct in the Korean culture. This organizational culture and structure could give a lesson to other enterprises, and eventually led to the social change of Korean entrepreneurship. It could not come into any reality unless the management assumes toils and 112 sacrifice in conviction and authentic commitment on the trust of human resources and potential. That is because it requires an investment and mutual trust without a tangible short turn. The mindset is, therefore, the kind of social, humanistic, progressive which involves a courage, knowledge, as well as moralities on the side of management beyond a mere myopic management priority. This could build up the trust leading to the ethical management in their industrial and social commitment. The ethical perspective would turn as desirable while the external and internal ethical pressure could be moderated (Yeager, S. J., Hildreth, W. B., Miller, G. J., & Rabin, J. , 2007). The ethics stress would more be easily resolved because they were humanly interacted and based on the mutual trust. It is needless to speak of job satisfaction of YK employees and their chance of changing jobs (2007). The firm actually purported to convert the kind of physical workers into some intelligible ones, which made a profound effect on the social ethos of Korea. Kook-hyunMun, a CEO of this firm, termed this paradigm shift as a “knowledge management,” which requires to learn as well as to be creative (2010). It should be a critical lesson for the society and Korea, and the progress within YK is notable with so high rate of participation in the learning program. YL offers a compensation for the participants, and programs were neither limited to the occupation skills nor work-related. The humanity subjects and social science were offered to foster the personhood of workers as a democratic citizen. His management philosophy had not rested within a small scale of firm itself, but projected into the neighborhood. The environmental campaign, designed and pursued in his initiative, had impacted on the Korean society, in the least, the basic understanding of Korean citizens about that issue. He seriously perceived an interactive nature between the corporate and society in the whole. The internal turf to oppose his vision of environmental preservation arose since his plan requires a sum of budget. However, it had shortly been proved that the environmental and ethical concept of management could bring a positive consequence about the social change as well as the corporate interest. Reference Yeager, S. J., Hildreth, W. B., Miller, G. J., & Rabin, J. (2007). The relative effects of a supervisory emphasis on ethical behavior versus political responsiveness.Public Integrity, 9(3), 265-283. Frederickson, H. G. (1999). Ethics and the new managerialism. Public Administration and Management: An Interactive Journal 4(2), 299-324. Ethics Resource Center (ERC), Organizational Ethics Articles http://www.ethics.org/resource/organizational-ethics Sung, S.Y. & Choi, J.N. (2010), The Leadership of Mun, K.H.; Myth and Success of Yuhan- Kimberly, Seoul, ROK: HANSMEDIA. Hunt, L. (2008). Inventing Human Rights : A History, New York/London :W.W. Norton & Company. Laureate Education Inc. (20o8).Ethics and social justice. "Philosophical Roots" with Amanda Baker (approximately 11 minutes) http://www.ethics.org/resource/organizational-ethics 113 Maccallum, G.C. (1993). Legislative Intent/Essays, Madison. WI: University of Wisconsin Press. Reichert, E. (2011). Social Work and Human Rights: A Foundation for Policy and Practice, New York, NY: Columbia University Press. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Human Rights, Retrieved Sep. 27, 2013 from http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rights-human/ http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rights-human/ 114 A Repository of Socratic Conversation Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: September 5, 2013 4:38 AM Hi. Domaneneicka. The organization would play an important role to nurture the boys and girls of America. It obviously would take the form of national system in branches and collaboration. Ethics in this case may involve a difficult educational issue on the conscience or spiritual cultivation of youths. The state of Alabama is notorious even to Koreans in the context of civil disobedience and other civilized concepts in disagreement or contention. You said the bond of youths with the grown-ups and aristocracies in the local community. How do you handle a possibly undesirable influence from the unverified indoctrination or ensure a sound system of youths to grow and learn? Thanks for your introducing a great organization, and I suppose that the organization may have a twin system globally. Regards.Kiyoung. Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: September 5, 2013 4:12 AM Hi. Derek. Thank you for the posting. Your organization seems interesting that the conflict of interest likely is self-adjusted. The board members, are payers and beneficiaries from the operation of company. It is likely a mixed nature of organization between public and private in terms of its commission and budgetary system. I guess that the income may be accumulated to the benefit of owners since it is a private company. Is the organization responsible to the shareholders? Do the board members work on a paid basis? What ethics, if any would be involved in deciding an issue of income distribution? Respectfully. Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: September 5, 2013 2:31 AM Edited Date: September 5, 2013 3:45 AM Hi Amin. Thank you for reading my post. The cause for and calculus from the troublesome sanction or war in other frame, never seems simple nor straightforward. As we share, Syria is a most persistent and acrimonious regime, and the international source reported its relentless continuance on massacre and persecution. Actually we know the middle Asian nations are religiously orthodox and in no probabilities being submissive or repentant if on the Koran. One factor is that they are culturally or religiously incurable to persuade. The other is that we can see some of imperialistic remnants to make them incongruent and less easily 115 defined. The branches or ramification in the society and their political interaction apparently confuse a point for some of constructive dismantlement or regime change. Despite their regime of theology, we can surmise a new wave of democratic group to reconcile with or reform the religious nature of absolute rule. These complicacies, as coupled with a Russian share with this country, perhaps led to a restrictive scenario of war engagement in the last announcement. In this nature of cases, we often consider a state sovereignty, international laws and coercive action based on the UN resolution, collective concept of self-defense, and so. In many cases involving the Middle east Asian states, however, the practical aspect in controversy and armed conflict seems not to be a sovereignty concept on the state, but likely stronger on religious sovereignty. Their pride for the Grand Islam or absolutism on Great Mahomet would not be misperceived if we have their contribution to the world civilization in medieval times. This historical heritage and political dominance at those times, as well as their aspiration to rise seemingly have aggravated their untamed violence problematic in the eyes of western intelligence. This is the case, therefore, typically deserving our attention between the morality or ethics and responsibility. Reason and social custom generally are a principal source of moral standard. One scholar also illustrated that a passion or intuition is another powerful source for embedding the morality within an individual mind. Their moral argument would not be dropped if they may lawfully kill the enemy of Great Mahomet. That is in contrast with Christian teachings, "Love your enemy." Most eclectic perception was institutionalized into the modern penal laws in a proportionality principle and reasonable sanction or penalty. I consider the Syrian authority may argue their moral loyalty, but I am dubious if their process is ethically or by ways of reason and law, tolerable. It biologically fails the global community and produced a mass of victims in cruel and inhumane ways. Ethics possesses the quality of system, institution, co-existence and humanly subsistence, interdependency, and organizational dynamism through the global community. Law might share a vast of these elements, and come closer to the requirement of ethics. Most of legal scholars consider the positivist law of extremist nature as illegitimate as in the case of Nazis’ dictatorship. And the quasi-religious nature of socialist laws also is subject to the criticism and international resilience from the western legal society. The context of present days contention involving Syria, in delicacies and flavor, emanates the confrontation between the West and Quasi-East in strands. They would not be a communist regime that they are Quasi-East. Their perception about the morality and political virtue are idealistic and absolute, but cruel and relentless, and likely disparage the balanced concept or proportionality element in human understanding. I suppose they are not identical in religion, but the tone or atmosphere overlap in impression. I consider the cause seems mature to ground a sanction, and some of practical points should follow in calculus. For example, one commentator saw the sanction is necessary to give a lesson to North Korea. The chances about some of possibly tragic military confrontation with Russia or China would also come into play. The capability on preemptive measure seems very encouraging on the side of US military. The consequence, however, may bring an eruption of retaliatory action in other region. We may agree on a little subtlety in difference from other cases in this region. I consider the positive factors outweigh a retraction alternative if Syria continues to miscarry the ethics of global society in their morality ground. Thank you for sharing. RE: Wk2Disc1KHedgepeth-main post https://wa.elearning.laureate.net/webapps/discussionboard/do/message?action=list_messages&user_id=_166828_1&conf_id=_602881_1&forum_id=_1505369_1&course_id=_3461476_1&nav=discussion_board&message_id=_24731891_1 116 Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: September 12, 2013 4:22 AM Hi. Kristina. I agree that you seem very penetrating the ethics and morality. It seems applicable that the ethics often is required in the settings of workplace and so. It is precisely true that the extra- marital affairs seem to fail both of work ethics and morality. That is in comparison with the moral demand involving a before marriage sex. Those also would be an example in irony between the passive dictate and affirmative one. Not always though, the morality often appears to be given in some of passive dictate than the ethics. For example, we may construct some of work ethics to convert his religion from Christian to Muslim in the end that facilitates the multinational corporation operating in the Arab states. If not to respect the work command to convert, she may lawfully be dismissed without any violation of fair employment statute. How do you assess this powerful influence of work ethics to intervene a sacred domain of personality? The other context in quite opposite may be illustrated with the case of forceful coercion to foot on the Cross. Of course, this way would be an effective measure for the soldiers to distinguish from the Christian people on hostility, particularly in the war time. The job ethics of dominant military on the conquered land may not see it seriously problematic, but we would see this conduct immoral. I consider those cases show the adaptive or circumstantial nature of work ethics than the morality itself. In any case, we often do not say “work morality” although we talk about “work ethics.” I agree on your view. Respectfully. RE: Ethics and Morality Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: September 12, 2013 2:45 AM Hi. Pamela. Thanks for the posting. I agree that the ethics and morality are a form of building good human character. They likely enable humans on consistency and pleasure to keep on their integrity. The breach of code of conduct contrary to the prevailing force of society would certainly disrupt a self or ego. This means a failure of self in a myopic implication and public education in the larger scale. Conscience is one strand between the two, but highly individualistic and might be a modern equivalent of contient from the Aristotle’s version. Aristotle said contientis not friendly with a virtuous agent or ethical administrators and governor. Hence the notion, conscience, seems more affiliated with morality than ethics, but could be occasionally not shared even in the name of morality. Then, the concept would be nearer to the religious dimension as we see the controversy of conscientious objector against the war. I like to know your thought among the three strands if the state could interrupt the person, say, a conscience objector, on the libertarian beliefs. If his belief is absolute and not swayed, is it permissible to abridge his or her libertarian way to build his character? How do https://wa.elearning.laureate.net/webapps/discussionboard/do/message?action=list_messages&user_id=_166828_1&conf_id=_602881_1&forum_id=_1505369_1&course_id=_3461476_1&nav=discussion_board&message_id=_24731423_1 117 you perceive if only the state has a definite say on morality? Any point in distinction in dealing with the issue between the liberalism and libertarianism? Respectfully. RE: Ethics and Morals: Kathy J Shelton Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: September 12, 2013 4:55 AM Hi! Kathy. Thank you for the posting. Next time I will make it sure to be seen a sufficient font size in any untroubled vision. You seem to do very good on your nursing job and cumbersome issues faced daily within your job responsibility. I entirely agree that the ethics are presumed on some of knowledge and intent dimension, and get variable on the circumstances. You may retire that your business ethics may become vitiated, but the morality still stands at even the aged years. So the ethics discourse, as you stated, would be “….on the accord that your upbringing, schooling, and practice are congruent with what is ethically reasonable to deliver the healthcare.” Then we may have some sense if we juxtapose those, “Professional Code of Conduct,” “Code of Conduct for the Multinational Corporations,” and etc, which are against a non-denominated, “Code of Conduct. The latter would perhaps be a (human) Code of Conduct to define a morality. Given this perception, the ethics would be an enhanced concept, but be contested still from the morality. As you illustrated, the right to die in comfort and peace for the extremely painful patients would rise. I also favor a virtuous agent, like the doctor, Jack Kevokian, but unfortunately their practice seems excessively controlled by the government. Do you see the current rule of judiciary should be sustained between the medical ethics and human morality? Respectfully. Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: September 13, 2013 10:46 AM Hi! RAE. Great post! I have enjoyed reading. We read that the state or political community in the Aristotle’s exists a priori from an individual citizen. This context of collective supremacy or presage of communal being is also found in his teachers, say, Socrates and Plato. For example, Socrates, in his dialogue with a friend at the imminence of death, had a high tone of preaching about the rightfulness to thank one’s parents and society. An individual can only be an esteemed being since he is bred and educated by the parents and society. He, therefore, objects to debase the legitimacy of death penalty, and thought to be honored if he were to respect the state order. This classic assumption, as basic in our dealings, would also be shared in the Confucianism of Orient. They conceived the loyalty and faith to their parents and state as a most ultimate beauty or fineness, hence, ethical and moral as inviolable from other social or individual needs. However, I consider this does not endorse a communism, monarchy or the type of totalitarian form of government. A dictatorship on the staticism, such as fascism, corporate or social nationalism, would also come defaulted as historically contested and proven. For another example, the former Soviet constitution set forth the duty of children to foster their aged parents as a public matter. However, I am dubious if that provision could https://wa.elearning.laureate.net/webapps/discussionboard/do/message?action=list_messages&user_id=_166828_1&conf_id=_602881_1&forum_id=_1505369_1&course_id=_3461476_1&nav=discussion_board&message_id=_24732129_1 118 yield any more effect than the lasses faire system about a faith to their parents. The constitution also prescribed the duty of denizen to serve the community in their highest of talent and capabilities. This virtue to view the community or politics supreme and not tempered actually has been dangerous on the historical lessons. Regarding the final sentence of posting, I agree that the libertarians may, in some cases, be penalized in accordance with the state law. However, it should be scrupulous as a matter of criminal policy. For example, anarcho-communism may be subject to the higher standard from the clear and present danger rule if we consider its possible evils on the sedition and insurgency. Hippie, one expression of libertarian idea, should have been considered in view of the constitutional right of privacy on one hand, and its harm against the society on the other. I rather, in this sense, advocate the delicacies and eclectic view between the state and one or agent. The balance test was rejected that the 1970 and 80’s Korea punished them for some days of imprisonment or treated as a petit offense. This is now critiqued by concerned intellectuals in Korea, who argued on its infringement on the privacy right. You also said that a possession of firearms is sanctioned in the State of Virginia. However, I am increasingly has some differing view that we may be prudent if we regulate more tightly for the public peace and against a high rate of killings from this context. Your thought?Respectfully. Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: September 13, 2013 9:42 AM Hi! Amata. Thank you for the posting. I found your final sentence touching on the Korean context in 1950; “it would be unethical not to flourish nor fight for the pursuit of liberty and happiness.” Sixteen liberating nations, in due cause, willingly engaged to fight against the aggression of northern communists in Korea. They certainly were virtuous agents or countries gladly assuming the massive risk of sacrifices and casualties in the Korean war. Hence, the friendship between South Korea and US has been strong and continues as President Obama stressed in the previous speech of Arlington Memorial. I regret, however, that the northern regime accused South Korea and US as a parasite or an object to be stricken off. They do not merely say “unethical” or immoral, but they go further to define the relations in the plot of US imperialism or saw South Korea as the kind of watch dog to ensure the US interests in this region. It is paradoxical, however, that they are a worst of human right record, but mentioned a bit the kind of center-periphery theory. They are highly scientific, and, of course, critiquing on the capitalist economy between South Korea and US. But they persecute for their political objectives and actually is one of world least economies in the statistics. They stress on a state sovereignty, but sustain a generations of dictatorship. I consider the points of ethics differ in our case. I like to ask how we could reconcile the conflict of ethics if we borrow the Aristotle’s idea. If in a Korean case, how could we see the difference between a friendship of two countries and northern accusation about the state sovereignty? Respectfully. RE: Bravo! Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: https://wa.elearning.laureate.net/webapps/discussionboard/do/message?action=list_messages&user_id=_166828_1&conf_id=_602881_1&forum_id=_1505369_1&course_id=_3461476_1&nav=discussion_board&message_id=_24792005_1 119 September 13, 2013 5:48 AM Thank you for Kathy. Your question is stimulating to see the nature of policy or administration expertise. Most of policy decisions, particularly in the federal system of United States, would involve a wealth redistribution or social justice issue. A scope of policy tools, say, programs, projects, action plans, contracts or partnership would have an impact to lead the society in some intended direction and often underlie an issue of economic assessment. While many competing interests or factors are considered, they often come secondary as any final point of deliberation. The federal government is grossly a provisional nature of state than regulatory one in the US. Hence, this aspect generally intensifies than the unitary form of government, such as Korea and Thailand. A dual sovereignty between the state and federal governments requires the public administrators more sensitive about the policy effect from their funding or granting to the state entities or other linked system between the funds and their obligations. Therefore, I consider the economic aspect approaches seriously as we see in the contention around 1930’s about the role and scope of public intervention within two types of sphere. This point of consideration, as you know, also matters with the political issues between the Republicans and Democrats. For example, the environmental policy may incur a different extent of federal measure, and reshapes the division of responsibility between the federal and state governments. Given the role and nature of public administration on this focus, this week’s topic dealing with the liberalism and libertarianism is thought very useful to see a philosophical foundation about the humanity, social justice, and economic arrangement. Also interesting is that we have a political party named and represented for the libertarian virtue in US. The controversy and departure seem to originate as centers on the politics, liberty and economy or property right. The Three Estates and their feudal interest fell to be contested in 18 th France, and the politics fluctuated although the revolutionary spirit of liberty and property right could keep sacred throughout. In my research, I can confirm that the libertarian school of thoughts or ideas obtained a practical feature in the turmoil of French revolution and Napoleon’s rule. Libertie is a French word to glorify the liberation of Napoleon perhaps against the prevailing hostility on Ancien Regime. A libertarianism seems rather radical than the liberalism with a principal point of identification between the justification of rule and liberty. Hence, the theme is fundamental in “politics vs. individual liberty” while the liberalism would come more squarely and in diverse aspects of humanity. In the course of history and varying politics of localities, the libertarian idea developed in different forms. More extreme is the anarchism, which may be shared by both capitalist libertarians and communist ones. Once I read the article about one of greater teachers in 1930’s US, who spent their later life in devotion to writings and growing plants in their garden zoned on their own. I could not tell his name instantly, but he, one of eminent socialist leader at that time, shows the pattern of their livings. In the historical progress on this ideal, Pierre Pourdon’s perception about the true nature of property and economy was articulated into the tenet of mutualism in the economic relations. The theoretical work of Peter Kropotkin also represents one ramification from the libertarian ideas, as read in his Conquete du Pain. He enlightened an anarcho-communism, which succeeded the tradition of liberty and personal autonomy. They, then, tend to develop a distrust on the mainstream politics and dominant frame of market economy. Their concept on property may be shown typically by their proposition of “personal property” rather than “private property.” They farm for their own needs and may get the products mostly handmade. They may, if necessary, meet to exchange their products, 120 but not for the commercial interests but on the mutualism to be lived in the liberty and against the hyper-structure of rule or governance. That might be similar with our discussion work in an analogy or feel if the context is non-commercial and mutual. Shabby, but intrinsic, and posed by some hyper pressure with any of grand topic or theory, but finally becomes liberated if to write and present. As a public administrator, the libertarian theory or tenet would likely lead us to some fundamental point of rethinking about the system, humanity, society and routine intoxication from the practices or series of policy decision. A most factor in reflection is that the public administrators are a trusted class to determine on serious materialistic issue and any desired outcome. They are also required to respect the popular will of society and act in the line authority or hierarchy in command and responsibility. Then the theory or tenet would go merely intelligible or indirect on their public responsibility. However, some points can also be raised in view of the bureaucratic ethics and their consistency or track unaffected by the switch of government or new directors. The libertarianism may, nonetheless, go dubious how much it could practically works on the policy makers or administrators. The Mondrean concept of market or Green peace group in Europe may be viewed in the libertarian ethos, and the environmentalism may profile in assessing the libertarian thought. But its influence would not be clear since it actually is a minor party or less organized group unlike the Republicans or Democrats. I hope this to answer your question. Respectfully. Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: September 12, 2013 1:27 AM Hi. Susan. I agree that the consistency and integrity are important to behave as an ethical administrator. The design approach, in the Cooper’s proposition, may help the way that the administrators may figure out what to do, and to find a right fit to address the difficult ethical dilemmas. This serves standardizing the ethical practice in an amalgam as a professional agent, as leveled distinctively from the lay persons and based on the general requirements through a respective trait posed by each issue. The practice would likely be an operating manual against ad hoc basis judgment, and facilitates an unbiased and neutral administration about the ethical dilemma. Without the inconsistency and integrity, I believe that any unbiased or neutral administration would be impossible. Respecfully. Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: September 20, 2013 10:56 AM Hi. Freda. I have enjoyed reading your thoughtful post. I agree that the external goods, such as power, money, and status, should be finely matched with the prospective officers, who possess a quality, character, enthusiasm and so. Galton once said that the respected leadership 121 has some of hereditary attributes. The version now may take some of differing concepts over the interplay between the internal goods and external goods. In the times of democratic rule, the educated citizens come to be eligible to practice their vision and conception of public values. That would be harder or inconceivable if we live in the Ancien Regime. You had been raised in Newark, which is your loved hometown. I believe that your attachment or enthusiasm as a public planner would not be questioned. It underscores that you also have a good temper with and respect for the standard ethics from the American Society of Public Administration. You made a point between the public administrators and elected officials. That generally is true as we learnt. For example, it would be same as Korea that the public administrators often times are convoluted from the lengthy approval contingencies. The red tape practice also would incur bureaucratic inefficiencies. However, the career experiences as a public administrator, later likely provide some of background to win the public election in Korea. The status would make a good career path toward an elected official, so that the values or principles may be shared, as you pointed, “political economy, social order, and popular sovereignty.” I am dubious, however, how much the elected officials value the concept of efficiency. Your thought? As Caroline Whitbeck stated, I consider the practical aspect seems important, and the administrators may be helped if to figure out what to do about the ethical problems. In his view, the kind of concept, say, defining a problem and generation of alternative solutions, gathering information would certainly be a working ethical process as we also learn in the Cooper’s model. The bureaucratic practice, then, could be a distinct preserve of wisdom precedent, at least, in each of administrator’s domain, and may serve a frontier-reshaping by the faithful and self-cultivating public servants. How much do you agree if the ethical issue is not merely a simple nature of judgment? Thank you for the great post. RE: Wk3DiscKHedgepeth-main post Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: September 20, 2013 9:44 AM Hi. Christina. The example would be best when we consider an ethical issue. Often the police is viewed a top ranked institution as a matter of public credibility. The police make a high impression on justice and their loyalty for the public, and they are a useful source of cinema and novel stories. Some gangsters or rascals would menace the community, and a detective or special unit counters to finally capture a culprit or eliminate the rascals. To become a police officer had been taken highly honorable in Korea since it serves a social cause, relatively high income from the tradition of underdeveloped country, and seniority system or national pension benefit. A high share of my students aspires for the job, and devotes much time to prepare for the National Police Exam. The income context decreased since Korea is now one of developed countries. They could not be said as of highly paid now, but the decades of economic recession and the job stability of police would still be attractive as a good career alternative. These points are for the Korean police officers, and I wonder how the US context operates. We generally consider the level of pay rendered for the public employees weigh https://wa.elearning.laureate.net/webapps/discussionboard/do/message?action=list_messages&user_id=_166828_1&conf_id=_602881_1&forum_id=_1505370_1&course_id=_3461476_1&nav=discussion_board&message_id=_25127462_1 122 about the probability of bribery, theft, embezzlement and so. You may agree if one way to respond with the depraved or unethical behavior might be to encourage their public impression and their value for the community? Also your statement about a hardship of Chief can be shared equally with a Korean case. The police officers generally are firmly tied in spirit and morale that they may go unethically further to hide their subsidiaries or fellows. I agree that the best way to find a fit in the ethical decision making model seems a proportionality principle between the culpability and disciplinary measure. The issue still problematic would be how to educate the petit offenders, the small theft, since their propensity would be same as the large theft regardless of their theft amount in dollars. Hence, the sanctity of organizations is still possibly to be tarnished unless they are removed or cultivated to be reborn as a good officer. Your thought? Thank you for this excellent post. RE: Domaneneicka McDaniel: Discussion - Week 4 Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: September 27, 2013 11:56 AM Hi. Domaneneicka. Thank you for your interesting post-modern prose or narrative on this stiff topic. It actually gets leading to the point convivially. Kindly allow to ask several questions. I wonder what the “political human rights” actually imply. Is it the same notion about a “political justice” that the human rights critique employs to satire a judicial policy on the emergent national needs, such as in the Guantanamo camp or others. You juxtaposed the political, party-political, and communal rights with the human rights. I got the point, but actually what does the communal rights mean? If you mean the political rights are the kind of suffrage right or participation to the government, those would likely be a classic human right. You perhaps indicate “power” than right? Then it should be placed in dissimilarities as you said, since both, say, the politics and human rights, had struggled. I also like to know if you think it better to exclude the social rights since they are “peculiar” from the modernization lawful value. Your thought?Respectfully. Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: September 27, 2013 11:16 AM Hi. Amin. Thanks for your Great Post, and I enjoyed reading it very much. Your point that the human rights are a political progeny than any superstitious ways on sanctity would fairly enable to see the realities and need of human strife to watch the progress. Your view would also corroborate with the kind of legal positivism from Austin or Heart to pursue any ground for the validity of laws. They saw the sovereign command only could ground the source of laws. Suppose, however, that the natural rights concept and American legal realism marched forward its way through the world history. I am afraid if you agree that there would be a sphere which a mere political majority could not take a control over. A legal positivism from https://wa.elearning.laureate.net/webapps/discussionboard/do/message?action=list_messages&user_id=_166828_1&conf_id=_602881_1&forum_id=_1505371_1&course_id=_3461476_1&nav=discussion_board&message_id=_25460004_1 123 the German tradition also rather finds the validity and effect of law from the social custom or legal fundamentalism, as slightly different from Austin or Hart and your version of political rights. For example, we would like a freedom of expression and, of course, champion the right to know in the context of pursuit of happiness. Suppose that the majority congress shut down any opportunities about the books. How do you tolerate if you are an avid reader to know, or publication mania? Consider if the property rights are not ensured on easy confiscation and condemnation from the Eminent Domain without just compensation, how do you tolerate your loss of long works and efforts to the brand new house and necessities? In the normal situation, a sovereign command, social custom or legal fundamentalism would not do those vagaries unreasonably, but who bet from that, perhaps a least possibilities. There are also the case of extremities in the two World Wars, and Syria now undergoes a contentious conflict. The international constitutionalism, as seen in the context of UN, was pushed forward initially from this conflict of politics and reflection to restore. The concept, on the natural rights and inviolability of human rights do not negate the public reason to regulate the society. I am also not definite on the truths of natural rights, nor sure to rebut the legal positivism. My intent is to see the good or bad aspect of those assumptions. In any case, the social rights seem more accurately fall within the kind of political process argument. The death penalty issue or right to abortion, on the other, would rather feel more friendly with the kind of natural law tenet. The practical test would be if the Eighth Amendment about the cruel and unusual punishment could be abolished based on the political consensus. Some group of extreme natural law theorists would not endorse an effect of such constitutional amendment on the ground that it would transgress the inviolable or inalienable strand of human rights. The right to same sex marriage or that of homosexuals are not a social right within the prevailing concept of classification, but a liberty interest or civil right about the personhood or privacy. They could be argued for a legal protection in the courtroom when the state power infringes upon those rights. They may seek a legal remedy to invalidate the heterosexual public record of marriage or imposition of fines on the homosexual relationship. Respectfully. Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: September 27, 2013 10:06 AM Hi. Derek, Amin and Eric. Your illustration about the recent stride within South Arabia and Somalia can signify the working concept of human rights. The right to participation in the government is a threshold to ensure a democracy. The implications would much be doubled if the women were afforded that right. It needs to be noted that the universal suffrage was achieved as late in early 20 th century, which included a woman. Both are critical to ensure an inalienable right to an equal freedom between the different sexes. We welcome the recent context of South Arabian achievement in this respect. Amin’s comment is also helpful to see the nature of theocracy in Middle East states. I wonder, however, how the religion in that region would merely suit a King’s control. As far as I know, the women in the Koran states can be honorably retreated from the western mode of livings. I rather fear if the enactment of participation right would go mere into any ornament or sham provision. The problem to ensure a genuine surge of 124 women within the government would lie in the affirmative action of government and society at large. I consider Eric’s point would be a prevailing view that the social rights would be seen a mere prescription or state goals other than right. They generally lack the quality to a concrete cause of action in the courtroom. They otherwise would operate in the public street to petition for a better law and desired congressional action. However, I also agree that they could be a right in some limited scope of social rights, for example, the right to social benefit in the context of ex post laws argument and loss incurred therefrom. As the society intensifies in communication and interplay, the right to education or free food program for the middle or high school students in Korea virtually approaches some kind of anticipatory right although not inherited from the God. So the distinction may blur in that perception as you said. Thanks for the post, and I have enjoyed reading it. Respectfully. Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: October 4, 2013 8:44 AM Hi Nicholas. Thank you for the interesting post. The context of military administration would likely be considered out of the normal constitutional ambit perhaps because it has the nature of special relations in the purpose of organizational commission and structure. I am dubious if the same extent of freedom or liberty interest would be assured of the military personnel, students of public schools, and government employees. The scope of these people would be assumed to waive, to some extent as required to ensure the organizational commission and purpose, their constitutional rights. This theory of distinctive treatment against the normal civilians has been respected as a matter of law in Germany, France, Japan and Korea. This legal principle has increasingly merged into a unitary yardstick for both groups with some exceptions still based on the organizational goals and special needs. So the chances to censure a freedom of expression in the military are greater, yet to be deemed permissible. The court, if faced with the claims for the damages, corrective measure or invalidation of dismissal and other disciplinary actions, would, in many probabilities, apply a different standard in assessing the argument on the constitutional freedom. However, I consider, as Kathy and Dr. T viewed, that the commander had been seriously prejudicial about the freedom of expression and equal protection of laws. The comment of drill sergeant may be received as the kind of hate speech against the homosexuals, including himself. This personal anxiety would drive Sergeant Monk to make a countering statement as a “discrimination.” The commander might see it a prejudice against the minority group, say, homosexuals, who would be legalized in some state jurisdictions. These points would favor his version on this event, but the manner and final disposition, given its severity and arbitrariness, seemingly could not stand as Kathy and Dr T. perceived. Sergeant Monk may well claim to remedy his grievances from being relieved from his position and banned from the unit. Respectfully. RE: Discussion - Week 5. Main post Rachel Morrison Author: Kiyoung Kim https://wa.elearning.laureate.net/webapps/discussionboard/do/message?action=list_messages&user_id=_166828_1&conf_id=_602881_1&forum_id=_1505372_1&course_id=_3461476_1&nav=discussion_board&message_id=_25761913_1 125 Posted Date: October 4, 2013 5:37 AM Hi Rachael. Your view is fairly ambitious and encouraging, and the dealings you implemented as a supervisor proactively for perhaps a discrete religious employee are thought to be sustained. The dominant practices, however, are not mandatory unlike a maternity leave or child breeding vacation. They possess an economic quality, so that could be exchanged in the labor market. I suppose it no less meaningful, however, if we review or explore to apply the possibilities of a Bentham’s concept on the public value within the workplace we serve, say, subsistence, abundance, equality and so. I may not be wrong if the religious need is any more important to each personhood. I doubt if any subsistence or abundance, in this highly affluent contemporary society other than Bentham’s’ era, can be perfected without a religious, cultural or social strand. Do you have the authority, in any case, to shape a constant and organized command in this respect? Respectfully. Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: October 4, 2013 5:15 AM Hi, Cornelius. I agree on your point about a due treatment of aged prisoners. The criminal justice system may serve several goals from the prevailing viewpoint, such as a retribution, prevention, correction and so. The dilemma comes in a similar context where Bentham sighed about the tension or incongruence between the public utility or value and sinister actors. Do you consider if a due pain for the criminals serve a human solidarity. It is a basic propensity and humanity strand to impose an extent of retribution against the culpable criminals. One day, I came across a newspaper article that the parent of Dodgers fan deplored on the sudden death of his son after a baseball game. He was struck on his head with the stool by other spectator, and the shock caused him to death. The perpetrator of that violence had been capture and investigated by the police, but acquitted instantly since the police found a self defense claim valid. The parents likely lost their sense of human solidarity, and actually that point was highlighted in the article. Of course, there certainly would be points of legal issues which lay persons could not apprehend. Based on the short introduction, however, I may get as same to the frustrated parent. Without a justice, the human solidarity seems hardly achieved. How much do you believe if the goal of retribution in the national penal system would explain for our justice concept? Is it a stronger point than other correctional or educational paradigm of criminals? How do you consider it better serving if the privatization of prison facility would be expanded? Respecfully. Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: October 11, 2013 3:30 AM 126 Hi. Cornelius and Dr. T. The issue of same sex marriage recently rose in Korea, and according to the similar context of US. One male held a marriage ceremony in the public forum and in the gatherings for media coverage. After the ceremony, he announced to dispute about the current system of heterogeneous marriage only. As Korea adopted a recordation element with the public record as a requirement of legally valid marriage, they would be frustrated even if they completed a ceremony. Hence, they would have a valid ground to question the constitutionality of recordation system and lacking of system to support their case. As Dr. T said, the incorporation clause can enforce a respective state to abide by the liberty or equality requirement within the Federal constitution. The court perhaps would not be expansive in viewing the class of liberty subject to this clause. Perhaps only a fundamental freedom merits to require the state to be bound, such as the right to free travel. It is also a matter of discretion, and in limits from the constitutional empowering, so it is dubious if the Fed would advance to regulate the marriage affairs. If the controversy invokes an equality, and often the ways to be dealt, the 14 th Amendment can be applied. However, I suppose that the court would be less positive to condemn the system of respective state on this matter. Korea is a unitary state on the same ethnic background, but that is not the case of US. This would lead to respect each state authority in this kind of subtle privacy issue. I am not sure if the matter is any kind of federal nature or necessary and proper to advance the federal interest. Hence, the Fed, in high chances for the near future, is expected to stay reticent or indirect about this matter. Respectfully. RE: Discussion 1 - Gender and Equality in the Workplace Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: October 11, 2013 2:57 AM Hello, Pamela. I agree that the gender equality has to be given a due respect in ensuring the workplace democracy. I consider that the pay equality and equal opportunity to promotion would be concerned most seriously. In the recent context, it is interesting that Korean congress women organized an ad hoc monitoring team by themselves against the male abuse of sexes within their House. In the past, one male congressman played on the demeaning statement in the informal meeting, which defamed a woman media worker. He was captured under the public criticism, and faced the challenges to be disqualified. In other case, a congressman subscribed to pornography in the official session of the House. The female team made an official statement to denounce such unethical conduct, and urged a proper response. As the society develops, the equality seems to develop in any extended complexity and diversity in fashion. Respectfully. Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: October 11, 2013 12:25 AM https://wa.elearning.laureate.net/webapps/discussionboard/do/message?action=list_messages&user_id=_166828_1&conf_id=_602881_1&forum_id=_1505373_1&course_id=_3461476_1&nav=discussion_board&message_id=_26099276_1 127 Hello Dr. T. The policy makers often deliberate on the point of what standard would be proper to design or implement their policy frame and goals. As Phoenix showed, the earlier thinkers would face the dilemma among the democracy, equal quest from a radical emancipation, as well as public rationale. They even detested a pure democratic form of government on an extent of fear and distrust. The 14 th Amendment, as you said, could give a standard that the bureaucrats have to refer to administer the complex nature of public policy, say, efficiency, fairness and creation of public value. In the course of public policy process, it is notable that the 14 th Amendment even allows a different standard of review, say, strict scrutiny, intermediary one, and reasonable test. The suspect classification centers on this theory developed by the courts. In the paraplegic case, I consider it to fall within the last standard so that the policy makers entertain an ample scope of discretion. On the other hand, a policy measure to deal with the suspect classification, such as race, aliens, and other some, requires a more prudence on behalf of the congressional or executive officers. It would also compose a bureaucratic ethic and the responsible administrator shall mind to review. One interesting point would be the “business judgment rule” which relaxes the responsibility of corporate directors and officers. Their personal responsibility would diminish on this rule even if they fail to meet the strict standard of care and harm his corporation. This rule then could effect to encourage an ambitious decision and in reflection of often unforeseeable business environment. I doubt, however, this perspective can apply to the context of government if the damages may be awarded from the wrong measure of government. Korean jurisdiction strictly limits a personal responsibility of governmental employees on very exceptional cases. The business decision rule may go toward the same point of concern about the personal responsibility of public administrator, which, in conception, includes both sphere. If the business judgment rule is enforced strictly, both can converge in the extent of fining a personal responsibility, but still the government employees are entitled to the virtually free context of policy framing work. I am a little skeptical that the mid rank officials, who are principally responsible to shape a specific policy, likely enjoy the immunity, which is similar to the President, Judges or Congressmen. The business judgment rule was invented, in contrary force, for the directors of private organization, but can offer some lesson for the governmental context. My regards. Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: October 12, 2013 9:45 AM Hi Cornelius. I agree on your point that an equal access to the court proceeding would say very much to ensure the justice and human rights. Indigent litigants may be afforded a special assistance about the court fees and other context. That seems particularly pivotal if the case incurs a serious criminal violation and potentially high punishment. You also suggest that the higher education and social or economic privileges can well lead to the different status of people. The court would once deal with the former context, but it is in their limit that cannot say positively to enact or implement. They would say only to rule on the challenged and extant institution. We often regret of no mandatory order to provide a free education or welfare program in the courtroom, but the kind of dealings should be around the politics or public 128 ideals. I like to know if any special treatment for the indigents, such as a free counsel or court-appointed attorney in the criminal jurisdiction or waiver of court fees in the small claims are afforded in South Africa. Your answer? By the way, please disregard the post mistakenly uploaded in the name of Derek. Respectfully. Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: October 12, 2013 9:13 AM Hello Nicholas. It is not unexpected that Michigan people favor a fair competition based on the learning abilities, scholastic aptitude and achievement on the basis of application. It is also problematic as you suggest if the students consider it as a usual course of dealing for the favorable quota. Korea also is very contentious if any unfair, of course meant in the merit based justice, factors affect the admission policy of university. Particularly, most of us have the notion that the academics have to worship of merit and intellectual growth. The counter thesis may look, besides the points on the “affirmative action” from any positive minds and “reversed discrimination” from the negative eyes, to the academic freedom of university and autonomy about the school administration. How do you consider if the school administrators see it serve a bright line of goals and can administer on a reasonable ground? Could they claim their academic freedom to select their student on their own scale and assessment elements? How do you see any difference between the public and private universities? Respectfully. Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: October 12, 2013 8:52 AM Hi Eric. Thanks for your interesting post. Your illustration about the disease and health service seems to allow us in a good comparison. One would voluntarily assume the risk if to be harmed from the tobacco use. Another person may be economically deprived that could not afford to defray their health expense. In terms of the equal justice to social welfare, the second case could be remedied if controversial in extent as in the Obama care. In view of libertarian concept of equality, the second case would be disputed seriously if to establish a prima facie case against the tobacco company, which claim the tort damages. How do you consider if the tobacco company claims their right to the original freedom on property and business operation? Do you see the argument plausible if the tobacco company has to be responsible since they stand on a developed footing about the technology and key information about the harms. In factors about a gross disparity in the economic power between the individual consumer and big tobacco company, does it comport with the social justice to compensate for the death of tobacco patrons? Respectfully. 129 Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: October 12, 2013 8:46 AM Hi Derek. Thanks for your interesting post. Your illustration about the disease and health service seems to allow us in a good comparison. One would voluntarily assume the risk if to be harmed from the tobacco use. Another person may be economically deprived that could not afford to defray their health expense. In terms of the equal justice to social welfare, the second case could be remedied if controversial in extent as in the Obama care. In view of libertarian concept of equality, the second case would be disputed seriously if to establish a prima facie case against the tobacco company, which claim the tort damages. How do you consider if the tobacco company claims their right to the original freedom on property and business operation? Do you see the argument plausible if the tobacco company has to be responsible since they stand on a developed footing about the technology and key information about the harms. In factors about a gross disparity in the economic power between the individual consumer and big tobacco company, does it comport with the social justice to compensate for the death of tobacco patrons? Respectfully. Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: October 10, 2013 9:44 AM Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: October 18, 2013 10:13 PM Hi. Cecilia. I agree that the girls would be one source for the national income. They work on the house chores, but I am dubious if their work value is to be converted into the statistics of GNP or that in per capita. We may have some of conversion chart, but is it dealt so? I also agree on the serious challenge you mentioned about the male crime rate at his earlier years. Is there any tangible measure from the policy makers besides the adverts or oral encouragements? If it were to be so, what extent of probabilities do you consider that the law or regulations in challenge would be brought to the courtroom. Respectfully. Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: October 18, 2013 9:53 PM Hi. Ahmed. 130 Thanks for the interesting post. The context can be applied at the global practices of bureaucracy and training scheme. We, however, would not have any definite sensibility in agreements. Korea once had the Sam-cheong Training Camp to refresh at an emergence of the militaristic rule in 1980. A socially esteemed people had to undertake a severe training in the group of criminals and innocent suspects arrested in the street. Korean bureaucrats often have a personal perception that his career path may be disadvantaged if to be committed to the educational institutions. This apprehension might not be shared with the US and other developed countries if they favor and see the life-time learning good to develop their career. In those countries, it may be one way to enrich their skills and expertise in the alternative for the long years track service in the key post. I am about Michel Foucalt on his churning of prison history. One other peer could be the idea of Pan-opticon of Bentham drawn to idealize a perfect prison structure. This way of approach seems to be required of public administrators. The educational institutions, often managed by key branches of administration, might be compatible with the prison setting, but I also see the tightened bureaucrats on his track also be seen as same. Is there any promotional discrimination if the Nigerian police officers with the experience to be posted into the School. Respectfully. Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: October 18, 2013 9:17 PM Hi. Nicholas. I agree that the LAUSD’s initiative on IPad idea concerning the redistributive welfarism could encounter any public criticism. I suppose if the food program would not be universalized through the public high schools. IPad is an expensive equipment that even adults may not use it due to his short pocket expense in Korea. I am also at odds if the IPads are dominantly for the learning distraction purposes, although you mentioned that there would be some points of concern about the ESL. As we know, the state government has long exhibited a fiscal pressure over the years. Is there any independent basis to collect tax on behalf of the Unified School District? What purposes other than the redistributive welfare would underlie the IPad idea? Given Sen’s functional concept of equality or ambition- sensitive from Dworkin, equal access to the use of IPads may be agreed. However, I am not sure if the students were to be essentialized on the device in any ways about the learning or other educational activities. I consider if the poverty or homeless people should be in any urgent policy priority? Respectfully. Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: October 26, 2013 9:19 AM Hi Ahmed. Thanks for the interesting post. Actually it would be a sad story that the girl was deported to Kosovo and allowed to be imported into France. As you said, the negative liberty is real and the positive liberty is the kind of power or capability as Sen noted. It has been really 131 ambitious to integrate the Europe, and place it under some of uniform public administration. The labor or social welfare policy could be shared in some extent, and its expansion may increase the positive liberty of European citizens. They now progress on the same currency of Euro, common recognition and transfer of academic credits, and many of common policies to facilitate the basis of individual freedom. In this context, the liberty must be positive other than negative. Hence, the level playing field may be assured in any uniform fashion, likely the evolution of US democracy and federalism, which enables an individual to be free to something. The privileges to interstate travel in the US may be applied to France and Kosovo, and the ambit of individual freedom would expand beyond the mere absence of obstacles. In other sense, it may be seen a negative liberty if we take a more universal notion about the human freedom to travel. Therefore, it seems relative in concept and direction. The practical issues in the European integration, I suppose, would trigger a wisdom of public policy and political consensus. It actually poses the challenges as we charted in the decades, including the financial crisis, popular dissention about the common welfare policy and disapproval of European constitution, and so. Given their integration, we agree that the ability to do something on behalf of Europeans would enlarge. However, the wealthier Europeans would be highly reluctant to endorse the European constitution in order to defend their property right and to keep the external constraints to be minimal, which would likely be as the kind of conservatives or libertarians are presumed. It is surely imposing if the positive liberty would encroach upon the public administrators. We could be aware of the dilemma and trouble if European leaders struggle with their tough policy agenda. Respectfully. Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: October 25, 2013 10:41 PM Hi Cornelius. The subjective journalism also once practiced in Korea during 1970’s and 1980’s. In their view, the wisest man can select the information useful or not harmful to the society. His or her ideal or vision perhaps would be paramount, and generally negates the competition of ideas in the market. The basic premise on the free expression and first amendment right could be undue until some of leader’s pursuit is completed. Hence, the normal apprehension about the liberty and equality can dispense way which presumes an understanding “born equal under the God.” Galton’s way of approach about the leadership quality or Joseph de Maistre’s belief would be more powerful in their case. In Korea, the context of 1970’s 1980’s government is still in dispute and feud about the identity, ethics, and political ideals of Korea as well as its legitimacy among the historians, which hovers around the industrialism and democratic fashion of rule, such as the free press and expression. The vision of economically developed countries can deserve a first priority for some of radical critique as in the case of Bismarck. As Koreans lack the phase in history on the absolute power and national industrialization, say, Queen Victoria in Great Britain around the mid of 19 century or the State Premier Wismark in Germany under the Wilhelm administration, they generally see it inextricable that President Park and other militaristic groups may reign to lead the country in their ambit and vision. Other camp, often democratic adherents, perceived it critical on a dominant ethos of democracy. How do you consider your native country in this frame of analytical lens? Respectfully. 132 Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: October 25, 2013 10:03 PM Hello Nicholas. Thanks for the interesting post. If people would often be staunch on their religious beliefs, it might go controversial. You just narrated the fact, and I see little basis to provoke any peer. It would be obvious that cutting hands is any cruel and unusual punishment. Stoning to death the women would also be intolerable for the eyes of normal humans, who committed an adultery. On the other hand, as the religious piety often shapes a dominant part of human subsistence as we believe in Jesus Christ, I also suppose it might be plausible for the Muslims in the course of justice administration to impose such a cruel punishment. The point likely underlies in the Eighth Amendment of US Constitution where the punishment should be humanly. We are surprised to see over 200 years of democratic history since 1789 Constitution has been gone as irrelevant with the Muslim states. Hence, their regime would be classed in more proper terms as theocracy other than democracy. In mere a shape of punishment, the Orient feudal history also exposes an inquisitive nature of criminal process, torture and cruel punishment. Hence, we also are skeptical if the “rule of man” could seriate the kind of Muslim, monarchy and communism. We also suspect what nature of human elements is governing or determines the dominant dimension of human as explored by German psychologist G. Freud. Some might be honest if the woman deserves a death who committed an adultery. That might saturate our intuition or the kind of id instantly. That might be most strong depending on an individual or even universally. In this case, the dimension of ego or in some cases super ego, which usually requires a reason and complex notion of phenomenon may get left secondary for them. In Korea, there has long been a debate about the abolition of death penalty. Often the voice of recognition had prevailed and the abolitionists failed to achieve a popular support. A logic and metaphor of advocates on the death penalty rely on the injustice between the perpetrator and victims as well as honest pathos of humanity about the rightfulness of retribution. Hence it involves points of concern covering the criminal policy and justice system, legal pluralism, the tension between the natural laws and positivism, and so. In any case, we may be wiser not to intervene a domestic jurisdiction or internal affairs of nation. The problem may likely be developed into the breach of public peace or harms against the international community. The notions may not be easily defined, however. Nonetheless we may know some course or pattern in the last half century. I also agree on your bright comment about Turkey. It is a bigger country which probably possesses the quality to take a leading role in the advancement of region. In my native country, the saying is “if it is small, it would more likely be cruel.” Respectfully. Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: November 2, 2013 4:17 AM Hi! Rae. 133 You pointed to a serious issue that the e-communication or business could create. I also share the fear and human indignity which the abusive or unconcerned management decision can bring about. While the ethical standard could not be strictly required of private organizations, the ethics and responsibility of business manager likely are only recourse the public could rely on. Along with the invasion of privacy issue, the e-business grossly is not amenable to public controls so that the business entities often are not in the corporate form, but largely limited liability corporate. A notion or value from the concept of fiduciary duty and other traditional ethics embedded on the partnership could easily dispense away. A tax evasion or other aspect of unethical management including the privacy issue actually is challenging. How do you consider any effective way to remedy this phenomenon? How much the education and training program about the entrepreneurship could save this predicament if it were to be mandatory? Respetfully. Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: November 2, 2013 3:48 AM Hi! Phoenix. Great post to see our reality. The tendency of employers on the incentive or bonus system is really awakening if the positive controls often could be acceptable. Some of firms in Korea, often on an advanced footing, also follow the kind of US employer’s practice. It seems to permeate to develop delicate grievances about the liberty and equality within the workplace. As the private management largely could go in his own judgment, it might discriminate the smokers or other nonconforming workers to the organizational policy. The employers in the US, concerning the labor relations, would be the kind of beneficiaries who are often unregulated or less intervened by the government. You hinted that the policy would be motivated by the cost benefit calculation. It may work to preserve the workforce in quality standard. However, there could be some of socialization issue if it could discriminate or infringes directly or indirectly with the liberty of person. Some may think that smoking is one way to pursue the happiness as critically related with the freedom of lifestyle. It could be patently offensive if his peer is afforded a large bonus. He may feel alienated or even punished if the workplace is any whole of his life context as often we conceive. In a disappointment, he may head around to rely on the lebens philosophie or murmur why we live. The subjective philosophy of vitalism or importance in the immediacy of experience, as held by Bergson, may have supported his long years of work life, but eventually proves devalued objectively by the managers. Managers would be a strong rationalist to support the organizational policy, but the employee’s personal dimension was affected. In any case, we often take it as granted that smoking is worst in the society. And this view likely is prevailing. As a smoker, I also would not recommend others to smoke. How do you consider why the public insurance has yet to be mandated to compensate the victims of smoking and how the incentive scheme could expand in the near future. Is it to be planned on the public enterprises or governmental branches? Respectfully. 134 Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: November 1, 2013 10:30 PM Hi. Trudy. Thank you for your practical points in the posting. The federal government, especially the court, seems to impose a rather strong policy in the purpose for some uniform fashion of FELA in the civil proceedings. While the civil procedure would dominantly be a creature of respective state and Erie doctrine were to be in a higher profile, the concept of federal common law seems to be on track about the labor dispute. I am concerned of what you actually mean about “At Will” concerning the state government. Often we have a notion on the Federal Supremacy between the state and Federal governments. How much were it to be variegated if the issue underlies the employment relationships other than the traditional scope of human rights? Is it really true that the state government entertains so ample a discretion or autonomy to manage the labor issues on their own? The employment at will doctrine, in my surmise, could be restricted to the private nature of contract. Your thoughts? Respectfully. Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: November 9, 2013 3:53 AM Hi. Eric. Your quote of Slotes seems to fairly lead us to any bright line of conceptions about the principle. They would be pivotal to sustain the ethics of public administration, say, equality of liberties, difference principle as well as public value for the maximum advantages of all. We would be bereft of human resources if we end at this point. Hence, the ideals or ultimate principles seemingly could be played out only by ethical leaders. The aspect of ethics would likely be viewed as a litmus test making it distinct from the pure theory of political power. In this context, your illustration of mayor’s failure on the ethical standard would be an ingredient in this area of concern. Often the argument or perception seems so persuasive so that we generally are empathetic on the role of capital or businesses and government. They are key engineers and actors to address the status and vision of society. Hence the leadership or entrepreneurship discourse would flourish, and new technologies have advanced the paradigm of business enabling the individuals to form a small or solo business than any other times. Some of small enterprises based on the electronic creativity now could earn a tremendous amount of dollars just on a few work in the internet paradigm. Now the ethics lecturers could attain a social popularity, manage their consulting service, and make a profit. Therefore, the ethics of public administration needs to be approached beyond the traditional form or narrative. For example, e-ethics can be discussed. However, still the check and monitoring context of civil society seems to come into play despite the diversity or pluralistic trend of ethics. A biological environment of industrialism concerns an imbalance in power between the big and small businesses. The monster businesses in Korea, which are small in number and what are called chaebol, could well be compared to the government in terms of 135 influence and social prestige. I consider two alternatives can be said about the ways to check and monitor the ethics of administrators, i.e., national and international. Some cases may do good on the popular recall system of elected officials. The civil pressure and the role of press can also function leading the government and enterprises to see a right way. An enactment of ethical code or law would be an immediate way to address the issues as in the international code of ethics required of multinational corporations and the anti-corruption laws as nationally and internationally pursued. With regards to this problem, OECD guidelines would be useful, but the progress seems not to be remarked in each national context. A bad aspect of international approach would be less practical to penetrate the issue to some root basis. Is your case one time incident or over long time? How would the local system operate with or without the popular recall? Is it the country which does not have an anti-corruption statute unlike the US? How much is it serious within the national criminal policy? Recently many beloved entertainers were seriously condemned in Korea who had a shot of propople, the kind of cocaine. Respectfully. Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: November 9, 2013 3:41 AM Hi Pamela. I agree that the criminal justice system is another battle ground for the social justice besides an econo-political contention. Stand your ground laws had also been debated, and the attributes of each nation would lead to a different design in some area of criminal policy. Given the sparse populace and diversity in demography, it might be wiser to expand the legitimacy and more space for self-defense. That could differ in Korea concerning those factors, as well as particularly on the right to bear arms. The culture and passion then would also distort the criminal justice in a variegated form. As much an extent of similarity with the model penal code could be one alternative to respond with the criticism. That could, however, face the challenges from an independent state ground. Hence I suppose it fairly difficult to assuage for social justice. In Korea, the criminal issue provoking the social injustice would be a burden of attorney fees. In sayings, “The richer being acquitted, the poorer should be found guilty.” It might be seen as some of Voltaire-like prose in some dereliction of 18 th century common law court on its delay, barrier from the nobility, masked judges of self-interest or social sections. A recent trauma would be the group of Korean superrich who was alleged to commit a fraudulent accounting and embezzlement. Unlike an Enron case, they often have not been delivered a serious sentence which disrupts the public sense of justice. One example to be welcomed, however, was a heightened frame of criminal penalty against the bribed government officers. It was achieved by the amendment of statutes. In the Korean context, the legislature has seldom been criticized because of the wrong or unreasonable criminal policy. The judicial branch had been otherwise. How is it in the state of Florida? Respectfully. RE: Wk10DiscKHedgepeth-main post Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: November 9, 2013 3:33 AM https://wa.elearning.laureate.net/webapps/discussionboard/do/message?action=list_messages&user_id=_166828_1&conf_id=_602881_1&forum_id=_1505377_1&course_id=_3461476_1&nav=discussion_board&message_id=_27312971_1 136 Status: Published Hi Kristina. Thanks for the interesting post. I also consider we often face with the challenge between one’s fair share and strict egalitarianism. Actually how we perceive or comprehend one’s fair share entails a tack of points entangled with the social ethos and system, individual virtue, culture, national moralities, and history. As the state governments in US are debted across the nation, it might trouble if not successful to pass the bills. They perhaps could no longer collect more money from the tax payers. How do you consider if the bill would be proposed in the next time? If in some greatest materialistic affluence or worst level, it seems that a strict egalitarian argumentation may prevail or serve as in decadence or communism. However, the concept of justice and one’s fair share could not be automated to sustain any level or quality of welfare provision. The kind of ethics dialogue may be similarly required, beyond the moral administration, of the deprived group or individuals if we are a part of capitalistic industrialism. In this line of thought, I suppose that the moral capitalism and bureaucratic ethics from M. Weber could make some of insight. Respectfully. Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: November 16, 2013 3:54 AM Hi. Gerald, I agree on the point that the employers are actually a prime authority to manage the scope of issues on his business. It bears a proposition of modern human rights about the property and economic freedom. However, I am dubious if the employers are so afforded both with a tax benefit or other governmental incentives and their autonomy of decision still intact. Phoenix’s view rather seems practical that the equitable quota may increase a mutual interest in the society. Some aspect in your viewpoint may imply some of policy failure in effecting the desired ends. The public may prefer a more prudent policy design which depends on the nature of business and some of mandatory trade between the incentives and hiring quota. The vets may not be inferior in certain jobs or businesses. Those may be targeted in primacy and as mandatory. Simultaneously, the policy design in other area of jobs may take its scheme as experimental and relatively expanded as well as in the option to choose between the incentives and hiring. I mean that a pursuit to the end consequence needs to be ensured, and that it seems not even economically meritorious to dump all the cards to the employers. Your thoughts? Thank you for the thought provoking post. Respectfully. Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: November 16, 2013 3:49 AM Hi. Eric, I agree on your point that the public education is sacred and deserves a due regard on its autonomy, faith and commitment. The unethical behaviors of teachers are really surprising, 137 particularly because they are educators as responsible to breed their students in any exactly opposite way. A cheating is unethical which would neither be controverted nor granted an excuse not varying with the organizational culture or societal expectations. I may add some more about a cheating in the exam context. In Korea, the TOEFL test regularly has long been administered, and some occasion suffer a post-measure null due to a cheating or impermissible conduct of the Korean test takers. A small allegation for the misconduct of other Asian countries also offer a basis to null the whole context of test. Other innocent test takers in this case may feel or ascertain they performed well, but has to obey the ETS decree of invalidation. That may comply with the requirement of justice since the test must have been stained in the whole. However, it may be compared with the Atlanta incident that the TOEFL case failed to deliver a justice specifically unlike that suited for the unethical and cheating teachers. This organizational policy of ETS was not questioned expressly by public or the group of test takers, but often creates an unidentified stigma for the foreign English students or test takers. The test takers could well be disposed that they are collectively distrusted or prejudiced from the ETS’ discrete dealings than the normal justice administration. I am not sure if they are refunded of the test fee. However, it would be obvious that the innocent test takers incur other costs or loss of time, effort and opportunity. The organizational culture of ETS may come reasonable as differed if it involves the international context of administration. I also suppose if it may be one example of segmented equity Frederickson presented. However, I verify that the universal quest for any more refined distributive justice comparable to the domestic nature is fairly strong in Korea or perhaps other countries. A discipline or sanction should be for the unethical or cheating test takers, not for the innocent others. Your thoughts? Respectfully. Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: November 16, 2013 3:00 AM Hi. Susan. Thanks for raising a sensitive issue. A pay rise or public insurance is certainly the point of primary concern the wage workers attend with. As you agree, the response from Phoenix seems realistic and plausibly addresses our current status. A unionization would serve the social justice and equity, which, however, should be economically inefficient and often felt the kind of feasant to merely reproduce. I would be a middle income earner in Korea, and pays much of taxes and public insurance in draining my gross amount to 70 percents in net. I am doubtful if any richer class will pay more than me. The social injustice or inequity is actually squeezing and one of power games in the society. I am merely strolled around several points as instantly inspired. First, the core concept of “competitiveness” has to be questioned. This concept thrills the capital, and they tend to accumulate their income or revenue for the future risk or some more profitable alternatives, and so on. That could distort a more desired status of social reproduction and can marginalize the worse class. We often rest on the idea as quai-religious, “natural selection or survival of fittest,” but I may suppose that the tendency on the capital is never a matter of nature, rather a mere superstitious interplay on the mutual distrust among the capitals and competitiveness enslavement. I consider a social consensus could be negotiated or turned into any reality. Second, we can have an idea that the earlier capital was absolutely subjected to the Royal control. The Royal 138 charter has been only a ground that they perform the commercial activities as we see in history. Now the logic and hierarchy were overturned that the narrative of economic freedom overwhelms (i) intellectually the concept of sovereignty, (ii) practically political power and (iii) ethically public virtue. A worse aspect of monopoly and dominance in the earlier charter enterprises now remains, but the state control or fundament has likely suffered a disrepute or been neglected by the economic power. Third, we would be wise to retrospect a potential of corruptive practices, which may be embroiled between the political power and capitalists. Of course, an enhanced ethics of public administrators across the global jurisdiction may get those incidents rare, but still the kind of transparency is one point of contention that the global enterprises often see as a barrier. I am interesting to know how Wal-Mart, the kind of largest and famed business in the world would run without the public insurance for their employees. In any case, I may feel not incorrect if to see the problem between the physics and humanity or society. In some level of inertia on the capitalistic wake of development, it seems to turn not economic or materialistic, but physical. It is paradoxical as if the fortune global businesses might be on a fetishism with the kind of public highlight, to see their art concept of product, show girls besides the brand new car, journal ranks of business size, business story or ads, but possibly in the sacrifice of employee’s basics. My regards. Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: November 22, 2013 8:50 AM Hi. Rae. I agree on your point that the ethics could make it different between life and death. We have bad cases in Korea that the basic rule of corporation, for example, a strict requirement about the division of ownership and management, were disrespected. Owner managers have to be ethical on that point, but some of them had, in many occasions, were criminally punished because of the embezzlement of corporate funds. The ethics issue would be one of popular corner in the news section about the bribery, sexual misconduct, embezzlement, and so. The current state of ethics in the workplace perhaps had never improved over time. The internet or new mode of livings also seems to foster a growth of ethics inertia or callousness. Today, we were reported that some video game was developed to depict a killing spree in the public school. It was restrained to distribute from the public reason. The kind of video games may do good for a leisure time, increase of active brain or so. However, it seems also ill on many of human or mental aspects, and particularly concerning an ethical strand. I consider, in the alternative, that a practice of meditation, such as seen on the Buddhists, could help to develop the mental or psychological status of youths and employees. I also share some of incurable realities, in regret as Pamela hinted, that some unethical actors or employees would grin in the hidden side of organizations. I believe, as you implied, that the successful leadership most always would be a triumphant about the ethics issue of organization. Thanks for the interesting post. Respectfully. RE: Workplace Ethical and Unethical Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: https://wa.elearning.laureate.net/webapps/discussionboard/do/message?action=list_messages&user_id=_166828_1&conf_id=_602881_1&forum_id=_1505379_1&course_id=_3461476_1&nav=discussion_board&message_id=_27895485_1 139 November 22, 2013 8:43 AM Hi. Pamela. Thank you for the current state of ethics in Florida. We, Koreans, have a same story about the dress attire, but in some different concern. The government regulation was enacted about years ago that the employees could work in no tie and short pants during the mid of summer time. That personal appearance or workplace scene may militate against a decent or loyal impression of public employees, hence, could make them less friendly with the public or clients. Of course, some opposing views sustain its informal or soft imagery as acceptable. In any case, it was considered to bring an advantage that the government can reduce a power consumption during the peak season. It also was viewed to increase a personal autonomy of public employees. I have been surprised to know that Korea is fairly short of power supplies, and the price will be adjusted upwardly for the industrial use of power. The ethics of workplace often would be thought in view of the social accountability, but could be malleable by a combination of external or internal conditions. The ethics code could be creative to double the public value depending on a specific leadership role, which leads to “one stone, two birds” as in the Korean case, i.e., the good public relations and economization of cost. By the way, how does Florida regulate the dress attire in their ethics code? Respectfully. Author: Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: November 23, 2013 4:15 AM Hi Rachel. Thank you for the insightful post. I agree on your view that the policy decision making, often reshaping the social attention with a funding and allocation of resources, would draw a new direction or public good, and hence social change. I consider the environment and national health would be two of most intense focus or contention in the allocation of national resources in US. It’s most advanced profile would perhaps be pioneering, and would later be contaminated into the second group of countries, such as Korea, China, and other new developed economies. The concept may penetrate a terminal of enterprises or firms as we see in the enhanced standard of environmental regulations, for example, Green Mark or others. Korea, under the lady president of administration, now champions the concept of creative economy. It is the kind of puzzle for the policy makers and concerned intellectuals how this leadership focus would bring a social change in Korea. I suppose that the policy makers or leaders would be more competent or ethical if to have a level of awareness about the nature of product, consumerism, decency of human subsistence, and others. For example, there is some doubt if we were to be too generous on the GMO products. The health care system would reflect on the national ethos and possesses the general nature of public good. How we could accommodate it in view of the economic terms would be serious and contentious. I may ask how the policy would progress in the prospect. Is there any chance that the Obama care would be revised? Respectfully. RE: Domaneneicka McDaniel: Discussion 2 - Week 12 Author: https://wa.elearning.laureate.net/webapps/discussionboard/do/message?action=list_messages&user_id=_166828_1&conf_id=_602881_1&forum_id=_1505379_1&course_id=_3461476_1&nav=discussion_board&message_id=_27933344_1 140 Kiyoung Kim Posted Date: November 23, 2013 4:12 AM Hi. Domaneneicka, Your post, on a prose-tone, has to be praised to epitomize a cynic, but veritable essences which we acquired in this term. Your mention, “the vicissitudes trade and industry and national globalization, environment fluctuations and the inflexible antagonism for advertises, deteriorating accepted capitals in the appearance of increasing inhabitants, and developing difficulties of transformation” echoes, and frontiers a long term reflexes on the mind of public administrations. As we consider, the Annalesschoolfrom F. Braudelor other perspectives, for example, Kontratief cycle from Russia allows some time to repose and recourse. Of course, we may see some of lament or criticism from the transnational ideology adherents, notably E. Hobsbawm, against the Annales school and so. I consider, however, that a long projected mindset, as practical and curtailed from the pure ideology, may work in some of persuasion and verity. As you said, the vicissitudes have to be charted seriously to unearth a public value and rethink the points of philosophical reflection. I consider OECD, UN and other science organizations would contribute much in this aspect. For example, the suicide rate compiled by OECD reveals Korea is a worst country. That would certainly be not the case in decades ago. What that long term trend on the suicide rate imply for the policy makers and administrators? Ideology, advertises, transformation may constitute the part of engines or dynamic factors for the policy makers, and could be a precursor to common alteration as you said. In other side, we can see a static, the kind of structural, long term science or assessment to make us on new plane or refurbish. In the progress, I consider the ethics or social change would be ensured a more focus under the circumstances where the econo-political narrative must certainly forge and require. Thank you for the interesting post. Respectfully. Reference Kim, Kiyoung, Fiscal Administration and Public Sector (March 22, 2015). Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2586039 or http://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2586039 Kim, Kiyoung, The Relationship between the Law and Public Policy: Is it a Chi-Square or Normative Shape for the Policy Makers? (September 10, 2014). Social Sciences. Vol. 3, No. 4, 2014, pp. 137-143. doi: 10.11648/j.ss.20140304.15. . Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2577832 Kim, Kiyoung, The Leadership of Korean Universities: A Case Study Concerning the Chosun University (March 30, 2014). Science Journal of Business and Management. Vol. 2, No. 2, 2014, pp. 50-66. doi: 10.11648/j.sjbm.20140202.12 . Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2577828 Kim, Kiyoung, A Promenade on the Ethics and Ethical Decision Making: Should Chae be Botched from the Korean Public? (October 1, 2014). International Journal of Advanced http://ssrn.com/abstract=2586039 http://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2586039 http://ssrn.com/abstract=2577832 http://ssrn.com/abstract=2577828 141 Research (2014), Volume 2 Issue 10, 15-23.. Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2577806 Kim, Kiyoung, A Reform Agenda of WTO Revisited: The Elements of Public Administration and International Organization (December 1, 2013). International Journal of Advanced Research (2013), Volume 1, Issue 10, 634-648.. Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2577787 Kim, Kiyoung, Amidst the Temper Across the Equality, Equity, Ethics and Responsibility: A Stymied or Pondering Administrator? - A Little Highlight on the Concept of Equality (September 1, 2014). Management and Administrative Sciences Review. 3(6). 909- 921.. Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2574739 Kim, Kiyoung, The Strategic Planning: Some Dangling for the Socio-Historical and Organic Lives (September 1, 2014). Management and Administrative Sciences Review, 3(6) 845-857.. Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2574732 Kim, Kiyoung, The Constitution and Tripartite System of Government: From the Mutiny for the Limited Government Through the Interbranch Subtlety. (September 1, 2014). International Journal of Advanced Research (2014), Volume 2, Issue 9, 392-401. Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2574711 Kim, Kiyoung, The Separation of Powers Principle: Is it a Lynchpin or Pushpin for the Voyage of American Public? (August 1, 2014). International Journal of Advanced Research (2014), Volume 2, Issue 8, 887-895. Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2573560 Kim, Kiyoung, Theories and Tenets: An Impalpable Troll for the Policy Makers, Research Officers and Administrators? (March 4, 2015). International Journal of Interdisciplinary and Multidisciplinary Studies (IJIMS), 2014, Vol 1, No. 8, 30-50.. Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2573526 Kim, Kiyoung, Human Rights: Are They Just a Tweak for the Policy Makers or Administrators? (March 3, 2015). European Academic Research, Vol. II, Issue 6, September 2014. Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2572951 Kim, Kiyoung, A Case Study Concerning the Strategic Plan: V2020 of Chosun University (.October 20, 2013). Science Journal of Business and Management. Vol. 1, No. 4, 2013, pp. 43-57. doi: 10.11648/j.sjbm.20130104.11. Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2572943 Kim, Kiyoung, Two Illustrations from South Korea and Some Reflections About the Public Administration Studies: Are We Granted to Pillory the Ethics or Social Justice? (September 2, 2014). International Journal of Philosophy 2014; 2(4): 48-59 doi: 10.11648/j.ijp.20140204.11. Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2571903 http://ssrn.com/abstract=2577806 http://ssrn.com/abstract=2577787 http://ssrn.com/abstract=2574739 http://ssrn.com/abstract=2574732 http://ssrn.com/abstract=2574711 http://ssrn.com/abstract=2573560 http://ssrn.com/abstract=2573526 http://ssrn.com/abstract=2572951 http://ssrn.com/abstract=2572943 http://ssrn.com/abstract=2571903 142 work_f3jnyu7bdnd3hbfilw4sxkf7au ---- The World Bank Legal Review Tilburg University The Justice Innovation Approach Muller, S. Published in: World Bank Legal Review Publication date: 2013 Document Version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): Muller, S. (2013). The Justice Innovation Approach: How Justice Sector Leaders in Development Contexts Can Promote Innovation. World Bank Legal Review, 4(1), 17-30. http://external.worldbankimflib.org/uhtbin/cgisirsi/x/0/0/5/?searchdata1=756966%7Bckey%7D#_ General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the public portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. • Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the public portal for the purpose of private study or research. • You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain • You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the public portal ? Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact us providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 06. apr. 2021 https://research.tilburguniversity.edu/en/publications/96b18e18-721f-4e47-b38a-3180aa297109 http://external.worldbankimflib.org/uhtbin/cgisirsi/x/0/0/5/?searchdata1=756966%7Bckey%7D#_ P u b lic D is cl o su re A u th o ri ze d P u b lic D is cl o su re A u th o ri ze d P u b lic D is cl o su re A u th o ri ze d P u b lic D is cl o su re A u th o ri ze d wb425962 Typewritten Text 74465 wb425962 Typewritten Text The World Bank Legal Review Volume 4 Legal Innovation and Empowerment for Development The World Bank Legal Review Volume 4 Legal Innovation and Empowerment for Development The World Bank Legal Review is a publication for policy makers and their advis- ers, judges, attorneys, and other professionals engaged in the field of interna- tional development with a particular focus on law, justice, and development. It offers a combination of legal scholarship, lessons from experience, legal de- velopments, and recent research on the many ways in which the application of the law and the improvement of justice systems promote poverty reduction, economic development, and the rule of law. The World Bank Legal Review is part of the World Bank Law, Justice and De- velopment Series managed by the Research and Editorial Board of the Bank’s Legal Vice Presidency. The World Bank Legal Review Volume 4 Legal Innovation and Empowerment for Development Hassane Cissé Sam Muller Chantal Thomas Chenguang Wang Editors THE WORLD BANK Washington, D.C. © 2013 International Bank for Reconstruction and Development The World Bank 1818 H Street NW Washington, DC 20433 Telephone: 202-473-1000 Internet: www.worldbank.org Some rights reserved 1 2 3 4 15 14 13 12 This work is a product of the staff of The World Bank with external contributions. Note that The World Bank does not necessarily own each component of the content included in the work. The World Bank therefore does not warrant that the use of the content contained in the work will not infringe on the rights of third parties. The risk of claims resulting from such infringement rests solely with you. The findings, interpretations, and conclusions expressed in this work do not necessarily reflect the views of The World Bank, its Board of Executive Directors, or the governments they repre- sent. The World Bank does not guarantee the accuracy of the data included in this work. The boundaries, colors, denominations, and other information shown on any map in this work do not imply any judgment on the part of The World Bank concerning the legal status of any terri- tory or the endorsement or acceptance of such boundaries. Nothing herein shall constitute or be considered to be a limitation upon or waiver of the privi- leges and immunities of The World Bank, all of which are specifically reserved. Rights and Permissions This work is available under the Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 Unported license (CC BY 3.0) http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0. Under the Creative Commons Attribution license, you are free to copy, distribute, transmit, and adapt this work, including for commercial purposes, under the following conditions: Attribution—Please cite the work as follows: Hassane Cissé, Sam Muller, Chantal Thomas, and Chenguang Wang, eds. The World Bank Legal Review, Volume 4: Legal Innovation and Empowerment for Development. doi: 10.1596/978-0-8213-9506-6 License: Creative Commons Attribution CC BY 3.0 Translations—If you create a translation of this work, please add the following disclaimer along with the attribution: This translation was not created by The World Bank and should not be considered an official World Bank translation. The World Bank shall not be liable for any content or error in this translation. All queries on rights and licenses should be addressed to the Office of the Publisher, The World Bank, 1818 H Street NW, Washington, DC 20433, USA; fax: 202-522-2625; e-mail: pubrights@ worldbank.org. ISBN (paper): 978-0-8213-9506-6 eISBN (electronic): 978-0-8213-9507-3 DOI: 10.1596/978-0-8213-9506-6 Cover photo: ©iStockphoto.com/Mark Wragg; Cover design: Nigel Quinney Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication data has been requested. http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/3.0 www.worldbank.org www.iStockphoto.com/Mark The World Bank Legal Review Volume 4 Legal Innovation and Empowerment for Development Editors Hassane Cissé Deputy General Counsel, Knowledge and Research, World Bank Sam Muller Director, HiiL Chantal Thomas Professor, Cornell University Law School Chenguang Wang Professor of Law, Tsinghua University Production Editor Matthew Moorhead Legal Associate, World Bank Contents Foreword xi Jim Yong Kim, World Bank Group President Preface xiii Anne-Marie Leroy, Senior Vice President and Group General Counsel Contributors xv Empowerment and Innovation Strategies for Law, Justice, and Development 3 Chantal Thomas The Justice Innovation Approach: How Justice Sector Leaders in Development Contexts Can Promote Innovation 17 Sam Muller and Maurits Barendrecht Legal Empowerment of the Poor: Past, Present, Future 31 Hassane Cissé Beyond the Orthodoxy of Rule of Law and Justice Sector Reform: A Framework for Legal Empowerment and Innovation through the Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities 45 Janet E. Lord, Deepti Samant Raja, and Peter Blanck The Political Economy of Improving Traditional Justice Systems: A Case Study of NGO Engagement with Shalish in Bangladesh 67 Stephen Golub Intellectual Property: Facilitating Technology Transfer for Development 89 Roy F. Waldron Contentsviii Transforming through Transparency: Opening Up the World Bank’s Sanctions Regime 101 Conrad C. Daly and Frank A. Fariello, Jr. Human Rights and Development: Regime Interaction and the Fragmentation of International Law 123 Siobhán McInerney-Lankford Legal Transplantation and Legal Development in Transitional China 161 Chenguang Wang Rule of Law as a Watermark: China’s Legal and Judicial Challenges 179 Stéphanie Balme Achieving Development through Innovative Constitutionalism: A China Story 201 Zhenmin Wang and Yuan Tao The Role of Laws and Institutions in Expanding Women’s Voice, Agency, and Empowerment 213 Jeni Klugman and Sarah Twigg “We Want What the Ok Tedi Women Have!” Guidance from Papua New Guinea on Women’s Engagement in Mining Deals 233 Nicholas Menzies and Georgia Harley Innovation in Asset Recovery: The Swiss Perspective 253 Rita Adam International Asset Sharing: A Multipurpose Tool for Development 265 Karyn Kenny Toward a New Law and Development: New State Activism in Brazil and the Challenge for Legal Institutions 281 David M. Trubek, Diogo R. Coutinho, and Mario G. Schapiro The Role of the Public Ministry in the Defense of the Environment: Hydrogeographical Regions and Attitudes for Coping with Socioenvironmental Conflicts 315 Luciano Badini and Luciano Alvarenga OHADA Nears the Twenty-Year Mark: An Assessment 323 Renaud Beauchard Legal Innovation for Development: The OHADA Experience 335 Marc Frilet Index 349 Contents ix Foreword Jim Yong Kim In this time of extreme fragility in the world economy, when the needs of the world’s poor are as pressing as ever, all who work or study in the field of economic development must constantly reconsider what’s working, what’s not working, and what can work better. Economists, scientists, activists, poli- ticians, investors, workers: all have a responsibility to carefully consider how best to contribute to the development agenda. Lawyers are no exception. Law- yers and legal specialists who work in the development sphere must engage in unending self-examination if they are to continue to make a useful, indeed essential, contribution to fighting poverty. The role of law, or rather the role of the “rule of law,” in achieving devel- opment outcomes has been acknowledged and studied extensively in recent decades. More analysis and debate are required, however, to understand the complicated and multifaceted nature of this role. That is a task that requires the input of practitioners, legal experts, and many others who encounter or work with legal systems. The World Bank Legal Review gathers this input from around the world and compiles it into a useful resource for all development practitioners and scholars. The subtitle of this volume, Legal Innovation and Empowerment for Development, highlights how the law can respond to the chal- lenges posed to development objectives in a world slowly emerging from an economic crisis. The focus on innovation is a call for new, imaginative strate- gies and ways of thinking about what the law can do in the development realm. The focus on empowerment is a deliberate attempt to place the law into the hands of the poor; to give them another tool with which to resist poverty. The two themes are linked by their shared importance in the face of economic uncertainty. There is an urgent need for new, innovative thinking, and a great need to empower the poor to defend themselves. This volume shows some of the ways that the law can make an innovative and empowering difference in development scenarios. Development prob- lems are complex and varied, and the theme of innovation and empowerment naturally has a broad scope. Consequently, this volume reaches far and wide. It considers the nature, promise, and limitations of legal innovation and legal empowerment. It looks at concrete examples in places such as Africa, the Asia- Pacific region, and Latin America. It considers developments in issues with universal application, such as the rights of the disabled and the effectiveness of asset recovery measures. xi Forewordxii The World Bank Legal Review contains many valuable lessons and creative responses. I hope that the exciting ideas in this volume will inspire lawyers and non-lawyers alike to consider what new contribution they can make to our shared poverty-fighting mission xiii Preface AnnE-mAriE LEroY The effects of the global financial crisis and the ensuing Great Recession are still being felt throughout the world and continue to be a preoccupation of the World Bank and other development institutions. Meanwhile, the Bank’s member countries face a range of other economic challenges and crises. As a result, demand for the Bank’s assistance remains elevated. In addition to re- sponding to debilitating crises, both real and potential, the Bank ensures that its resources are focused on the long, hard road to economic development. The Bank’s team of lawyers and legal specialists has a crucial role to play in proactively supporting the Bank in the achievement of its development objectives. It is our responsibility to provide a sound legal response to these many challenges. It is also our responsibility to ensure that that response rep- resents world’s best practice and is at the cutting edge of contemporary think- ing about what the law can and should do to support development goals. With these responsibilities in mind, we have compiled the fourth volume of The World Bank Legal Review, subtitled Legal Innovation and Empowerment for Development. In a time of difficulty and change, innovative ideas and strate- gies to empower the poor are more important than ever. Many (although not all) of the contributions to this volume of The World Bank Legal Review emerged from the second annual World Bank Law, Justice and Development Week, held in Washington, D.C., in November 2011. Jointly hosted by the General Counsels of all the World Bank Group organizations, the Law, Justice and Development Week brought together leading scholars, legal practitioners, development experts, policy institutes, universities, and other concerned parties to share lessons and inspiration. A sense of the great range of legal innovations and empowerment strategies that were discussed and debated is captured in this book. All of the diverse issues under discussion were linked by the understanding that the law must respond with solutions that are innovative and empowering. New problems call for new answers. I thank the contributors to this volume. The diverse topics they discuss and the varied perspectives they represent have been organized by four dis- tinguished editors: Chenguang Wang of Tsinghua University, Sam Muller of the Hague Institute for the Internationalization of Law (HiiL), Chantal Thomas of Cornell University, and our Deputy General Counsel for Knowledge and Prefacexiv Research, Hassane Cissé. Dr. Nigel Quinney provided invaluable editorial as- sistance. This volume deals with important and intriguing topics in law and development, and the contributors’ analyses will assist anyone who is inter- ested, the place of law on today’s development agenda. xv Contributors Rita Adam is Vice-Director of the Directorate of Public International Law (DPIL) at the Swiss Federal Department of Foreign Affairs (FDFA). At the DPIL, she leads the Division of International Law, International Treaties and the Law of Neighbouring States. Ms. Adam also serves as the Ambassador of Switzerland to the Principality of Liechtenstein (based in Bern). Before joining the FDFA in 1999, she worked as a legal advisor in civil and criminal mat- ters at the District Court of Thun, Switzerland. After assignments at the Swiss Mission to the United Nations in Geneva and the Embassy of Switzerland in Pretoria, South Africa, she returned to Bern in 2001 to join the Political Af- fairs Division, where she was appointed Deputy Head of the International Organizations and Host-Country Policy Section in 2004. In 2005, Ms. Adam became Head of the Legal Affairs and Press Service of the Swiss Embassy in Paris, France. From 2008 until July 2010, she was in charge of the Multilateral Peace Policy Section of the Political Affairs Division before being appointed Vice-Director of the DPIL. Ambassador Adam graduated from the University of Bern Law Faculty in 1996 as an attorney at law. Luciano Alvarenga is a professor and associate researcher at the Brazilian Society for Scientific Progress. His research focuses on the interrelationship between law and a variety of other subject areas, such as art and science, the maintenance of the Cerrado biome, environmental and forestry legislation directed at biodiversity, otherness and environmental justice, responsibility for risk and environmental damage, ethics, and new theoretical and meth- odological approaches in the environmental sciences. Professor Alvarenga graduated from the Federal University of Minas Gerais with a law degree, having been awarded a scholarship from the National Council for Scientific and Technological Development. He also holds an M.S. in Natural Sciences from the Federal University of Ouro Preto, Brazil, and a Specialist’s Degree in Environment, Education and Sustainability from the University of Evora, Portugal. Luciano Badini has been a prosecutor at the Public Ministry of Minas Gerais (PMMG) since 1993. He has also served as Coordinator of the Operational Support Center for District Attorneys Working on Environmental Protection, Coordinator of Interstate Justice Prosecutors for the Protection of the São Fran- cisco River, and Executive Coordinator of the agreement between the PMMG and the World Bank that aims at technical and technological improvements of the PMMG for the protection of the environment. He was the recipient of the 2010 Innovare Award for his work in implementing the project that organized the Public Ministry’s actions for the protection of natural resources of all river basins in the state of Minas Gerais. Contributorsxvi Stéphanie Balme is a research fellow at Sciences Po Paris and professor at the Centre for International Studies and Research (CERI) and the Paris School of International Affairs (PSIA), and the head of the “Law, Justice, and Society in China” program. Her research and teaching focuses include comparative con- stitutional law and rule of law developments. Her research applies to “emerg- ing countries,” in particular China and post-socialist countries. She lived in mainland China and Hong Kong SAR, China for many years, working at Tsing- hua University Law School as a delegate for the Civil Law Initiative and the Chinese University of Hong Kong. She has authored six books and a number of other academic publications and public policy papers in English, Chinese, and French. She also is a consultant on China for European and international organizations. Maurits Barendrecht is Academic Director at HiiL and has been a professor of private law at Tilburg University since 1992. He practiced law at a ma- jor Dutch law firm from 1982 to 1997. He studies dispute systems (e.g., legal procedures and informal dispute mechanisms) from an interdisciplinary per- spective, and systematically looks for knowledge from other disciplines (e.g., economics and organization theory) that can be integrated with best practices in order to improve dispute systems for the people who rely on them. His re- search is conducted through the Tilburg Institute for Interdisciplinary Studies of Civil Law and Conflict Resolution Systems. Professor Barendrecht has led several large-scale innovation projects in the area of justice and governance that directly addressed urgent needs not being met through existing legal ar- rangements. These interactive research and development projects usually take place in cooperation with stakeholders such as client groups, ministries of jus- tice, the judiciary, and the legal-services community. Renaud Beauchard, a French national and U.S. resident, is an attorney and le- gal consultant specializing in rule of law, justice reforms, and anti-corruption. A fellow of the Institut des Hautes Études sur la Justice in Paris and counsel for the law offices of Peter C. Hansen in Washington, D.C., Mr. Beauchard practiced law in France for six years as a litigator in a maritime and transpor- tation law. More recently, he has worked as a consultant for the World Bank’s Office of Evaluation and Suspension and for the U.S. Millennium Challenge Corporation on its Access to Justice program in Benin. Mr. Beauchard has written several publications on topics as diverse as international assets recov- ery, corporate social responsibility, anti-corruption, and the evaluation of legal systems. He holds law degrees from Poitiers University (LL.M.), Cambridge University (LL.M.), and Tulane University Law School (J.D.), and has both practiced and taught law. Peter Blanck is University Professor at Syracuse University, Chairman of the Burton Blatt Institute, also at Syracuse University, and Honorary Professor, Centre for Disability Law and Policy, National University of Ireland, Gal- way. He has published widely on the Americans with Disabilities Act and re- lated laws, serves as Chairman of the Global Universal Design Commission (GUDC), and has practiced law at Covington & Burling, where he served as Contributors xvii law clerk to the late Honorable Carl McGowan of the United States Court of Appeals for the D.C. Circuit. Professor Blanck’s recent books include Disability Civil Rights Law and Policy (with Hill, Siegal & Waterstone) (2009), Race, Ethnic- ity, and Disability: Veterans and Benefits in Post-Civil War America (with Logue) (2010); and eQuality 3.0: Towards a Right to the Web for People with Cognitive Disabilities (forthcoming). He received a J.D. from Stanford University, where he was President of the Stanford Law Review, and a Ph.D. in Psychology from Harvard University. Hassane Cissé, a national of Senegal, joined the World Bank in 1997 after serv- ing for several years as Counsel at the International Monetary Fund. He has been Deputy General Counsel, Knowledge and Research, of the Bank since 2009. In this capacity he advises on strategic legal issues facing the Bank and leads the Bank’s work on law, justice, and development. Previously, Mr. Cissé served as Chief Counsel for Operations Policy of the World Bank. He is the editor-in-chief of the World Bank’s Law, Justice and Development Series and has published papers on rule of law and development and on international economic law matters. Mr. Cissé obtained his LL.B from Dakar University in Senegal. He also holds an LL.M degree from Harvard Law School, graduate law degrees from the universities of Paris I Panthéon-Sorbonne and Paris II Panthéon-Assas, as well as a graduate degree in history from Paris I Panthéon- Sorbonne University. He is a member of the World Economic Forum’s Global Agenda Council on the Rule of Law. Diogo R. Coutinho is an Associate Professor of Law at the University of São Paulo, where his courses include economic law, political economy, and law and development, and a research fellow at the Brazilian Center of Analysis and Planning (CEBRAP). Currently, he serves as investigator of LANDS, the project on Law and the New Developmental State. He was a researcher at FGV São Paulo Law School and at the Brazilian Society of Public Law. Also, he was a visiting professor at the London-based Center for Transnational Legal Studies (2009). Professor Coutinho has written on law and development; ad- ministrative, economic, and social law; and regulatory and antitrust policies in Brazil. He holds an M.Sc. from the London School of Economics and Politi- cal Science (2002) and a doctorate from the University of São Paulo Faculty of Law (2003). Conrad C. Daly is a Legal Consultant for the Operations Policy practice group of the World Bank’s Legal Vice Presidency, where he has been engaged princi- pally in the Bank’s work in governance and anti-corruption. Mr. Daly gradu- ated from a dual-degree program between Cornell Law School and the Ecole de droit de la Sorbonne (Université Paris I Panthéon-Sorbonne). He is also a graduate of Heythrop College, University of London, where he read for a Mas- ter in systematic theology, and of Boston College, where he double-majored in biochemistry and history. While in Paris as a visiting fellow at the Université Panthéon-Assas (Paris 2), he researched issues in competition law and taught classes in U.S. and British constitutional and administrative law. His work experience also includes work with GRC Counsel, as well as legal internships Contributorsxviii at the German gas and engineering company, Linde AG, and at the U.S. Court of International Trade. Prior to making law his chosen profession, Mr. Daly worked at the Southern Medical Journal as the special projects editor. Frank Fariello, a graduate of Brown University and New York University School of Law, is currently Lead Counsel, Operations Policy, in the World Bank’s Legal Vice Presidency (LEG). He is LEG’s primary focal point for the Bank’s sanctions regime and governance and anticorruption policies. In that capacity, he coordinated the recent comprehensive reforms of the Bank’s sanc- tions process and advised Integrity Vice Presidency in connection with the Agreement on Mutual Enforcement of Debarment Decisions among Multilat- eral Development Banks. Before joining the Bank in 2005, Mr. Fariello worked for nine years at the International Fund for Agricultural Development (IFAD) as Senior Counsel and subsequently as Special Advisor to the Vice President. For the first ten years of his career, prior to his service at IFAD, he practiced corporate law, with an emphasis on international financial transactions, at a number of New York firms, including Skadden Arps Slate Meagher and Flom. Marc Frilet is the managing partner of the Paris law firm Frilet Société d’Avocats, which specializes in construction, infrastructure, and mining proj- ects, in France and internationally, with a particular focus on developing na- tions, mostly in Africa. The firm is also active in general corporate and privati- zation law. He teaches international investment law at the University of Paris V: Descartes and mining law at l’Ecole de Mines. He is a frequent lecturer and author, and the former co-chair of Committee T, an international construc- tion project of the International Bar Association (IBA), and a former Council member of the IBA. Mr. Frilet is Secretary General of the French Institute of International Legal Experts, sponsored by the Paris Bar. Stephen Golub is an adjunct professor, attorney, and consultant, who teaches courses on International Development and Legal Empowerment at the Uni- versity of California at Berkeley Law School and at the Central European University Public Policy Department in Budapest. He has edited volumes on legal empowerment and related topics for the Ford Foundation, the Open Society Foundations, the International Development Law Organization, the Hague Journal on the Rule of Law, and the Asian Development Bank. He has more than 25 years of experience in 40 countries, consulting and conducting research on legal empowerment, traditional justice systems, the rule of law, and governance for the World Bank, the Carnegie Endowment for Interna- tional Peace, Amnesty International, development institutions, foundations, policy institutes, and nongovernmental groups. Professor Golub has written over 30 published pieces for law journals, aid agencies, and other policy and scholarly outlets. Georgia Harley is an Executive Legal Adviser with the Australian Depart- ment of Foreign Affairs and Trade and a Legal Consultant for the Justice Re- form Unit of the Legal Vice Presidency at the World Bank. At the Bank, Ms. Harley works for the Justice for the Poor program, and is engaged principally on natural resource governance in fragile states. Previously, she served in the Contributors xix Office of International Law at the Australian Attorney-General’s Department, the Regional Assistance Mission to Solomon Islands, and on various rule of law projects in Southeast Asia and the Pacific. Ms. Harley earned a Bachelor of Arts and Bachelor of Laws (Hons.) from the University of Queensland, an LL.M. in International Law from the Australian National University and a Masters in International Development Policy (Applied Economics and Peace and Conflict Resolution) from Duke University. Karyn Kenny is an International Attorney Advisor for the U.S. Department of Justice, responsible for negotiating asset sharing agreements and building global capacity in anti-money laundering sectors. A former justice expert con- sultant for the World Bank, she served as a U.S. Supreme Court Fellow in 2007, one of four Fellows selected from an international pool by a commission appointed by Chief Justice John G. Roberts. In 2006, she served as a U.S. Ful- bright Scholar in Lithuania, teaching comparative constitutional and criminal law. She has served as an Assistant United States Attorney prosecuting federal economic crimes and as an Assistant District Attorney in the Manhattan Dis- trict Attorney’s Office prosecuting violent street crime. Ms. Kenny teaches law internationally and has received an award for outstanding teaching. A pub- lished author on international legal issues, she frequently serves as an expert speaker, including presentations for the Brookings Institution and the World Bank. Jeni Klugman is the Director of Gender and Development at the World Bank Group. Prior to taking up this position, Ms. Klugman was the director and lead author of three global Human Development Reports (2010, 2011, and 2012) pub- lished by the United Nations Development Programme. From 1992 to 2008, she held various positions at the World Bank, focusing on poverty, inequality, and human development in low-income countries in Africa, Europe, and Asia. She currently serves on the World Economic Forum’s Advisory Board on Sus- tainability and Competitiveness and is a fellow of the Human Development and Capabilities Association. Ms. Klugman has published books, papers, and reports on topics ranging from poverty reduction strategies and labor markets to conflict, health reform, education, and decentralization. She holds a Ph.D. in Economics from the Australian National University, as well as postgradu- ate degrees in Law and in Development Economics from Oxford University, where she was a Rhodes Scholar. Janet Lord is an international lawyer and development practitioner with more than 20 years of professional experience. Ms. Lord directs the human rights and disability inclusive development practice at BlueLaw International LLP and provides subject matter expertise in human rights law and policy reform, advocacy, monitoring and complaints mechanisms, election access for margin- alized populations, building and strengthening national human rights institu- tions, and international disability rights. She also serves as Senior Research Associate at the Harvard Law School Project on Disability and is Adjunct Pro- fessor of Law at the University of Maryland Francis King Carey School of Law. She is internationally recognized for subject-matter expertise in the area Contributorsxx of human rights for marginalized populations, inclusive development, and disability and has authored a wide array of scholarly, as well as practitioner- oriented international law, development, and human rights publications. She holds an LL.B. and an LL.M. in law from the University of Edinburgh, and an LL.M. in international and comparative law from the George Washington University Law School. Siobhán McInerney-Lankford is Senior Counsel in the World Bank Legal Vice Presidency and former Senior Policy Officer, Institutions, Law and Partner- ships for Human Rights, Nordic Trust Fund, Operations Policy and Country Services. She has been advising the World Bank on human rights law issues since 2002 and regularly represents the World Bank in international human rights fora, including at the United Nations (UN), European Union (EU), and Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development (OECD). From 2006 to 2008, she served as chair of the OECD DAC Human Rights Task Team and was World Bank representative to the UN High-Level Task Force on the Right to Development from 2007 to 2009. Before joining the World Bank, she worked in private practice in Washington, D.C. She has published widely on human rights law and teaches occasionally. Dr. McInerney-Lankford holds an LL.B. from Trinity College, Dublin, an LL.M. from Harvard Law School, and a B.C.L and D.Phil. in EU human rights law from Oxford University. Nicholas Menzies is a Justice Reform Specialist in the Legal Vice Presidency of the World Bank. He works on institutional reform of the formal justice sec- tor and on mainstreaming justice into development programming with the Justice for the Poor program, with particular interests in impact evaluation, indicators, and gender. Prior to the World Bank, he worked at the intersections of plural legal systems as a land and natural resources lawyer for indigenous communities in Australia, on legal empowerment and access to justice issues in Cambodia, and in providing policy advice to the Papua New Guinean cabi- net. Mr. Menzies has an LL.B. and a B.A. from the University of Sydney and a Master of Public Policy degree from the Hertie School of Governance, Berlin. Sam Muller is the founding Director of HiiL. He has also served as Special Adviser to the Registrar on External Relations at the International Criminal Court (ICC), interim Deputy Director of the Common Services Division, and Acting Director of the Public Information and Documentation Section of the Registry. Before heading up the Advance Team to set up the ICC, he worked as Senior Legal Adviser and head of the Legal Department of the Registry of the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia and as a legal officer at the headquarters of the UN Relief and Works Agency in Gaza. In the mid-1990s he was Associate Professor and Programme Coordinator of the Public International Law LL.M. programme of Leiden University. Mr. Muller holds a law degree and a doctorate from Leiden University. He has published and spoken extensively on various topics, focusing on the law of international organizations, international justice issues, and, over the past two years, global legal trends and justice innovation. He serves on various boards, including The Hague Prize Foundation, and is chairman of the Board of the Hague Academic Coalition and of the Rule of Law Action Council of the World Economic Forum. Deepti Samant Raja is the Director of International Programs at the Burton Blatt Institute, Syracuse University. Samant Raja has over seven years of work experience in promoting the social inclusion and economic empowerment of people with disabilities. She has worked on mainstreaming disability in pov- erty reduction and development programs, developing programs to promote access to low-cost assistive devices for people with disabilities in resource- limited environments, ICT accessibility, and full participation in the labor market. She worked for the Secretariat of the Global Partnership for Disability and Development, managing research and knowledge translation activities. Ms. Samant Raja has published and presented on ICT accessibility in develop- ment and the implications of the Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities on employment outcomes. She holds an M.S. in Rehabilitation Counseling (University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign), an M.S. in Electrical Engineering (University of California–Irvine), and a B.A. in Telecommunica- tion Engineering (University of Mumbai). Mario Schapiro is a full-time professor of law at Getulio Vargas Foundation School of Law (FGV Law School), where his courses include law and develop- ment, administrative law, competition law, and law and finance. Currently, he serves as investigator of LANDS, the project on Law and the New De- velopmental State, and also as investigator of the Brazilian Institute of Ap- plied Research (IPEA), a project on legal capacity for development. He was a visiting researcher at the Columbia Law School (2008) and visiting scholar at King’s College London (2012). Professor Schapiro has written on law and development, administrative law, economic law, and, his main area of interest, the governance of industrial policy and development policies as a whole. He holds a master’s from the University of São Paulo Faculty of Law (2005) and a doctorate from the University of São Paulo Faculty of Law (2009). Yuan Tao is Counsel at the Environmental and International Law practice group of the Legal Vice Presidency of the World Bank, where he works on sustainable development, climate change, environmental and social safeguard policies of the World Bank, and Global Environmental Facility operations. Be- fore joining the World Bank, Mr. Tao served as an Editor of the Harvard Envi- ronmental Law Review, and practiced law with the international law firm Allen & Overy LLP in Beijing, China, and London, where he advised on various in- ternational and environmental law issues. His experience also includes advis- ing on legal aspects in relation to China’s business environment, foreign direct investment, financial regulations, and anti-corruption. He obtained his LL.M. degree from Harvard Law School. Previously, he graduated with an LL.B. and an LL.M. from Tsinghua University, China, and an LL.M. from University Col- lege London, England. Chantal Thomas is Professor of Law at Cornell University Law School, where her courses include International Trade and Development Law and Interna- tional Labor Law. She also directs the Clarke Initiative for Law and Develop- ment in the Middle East and North Africa. Prior to joining Cornell, Professor Contributors xxi Thomas chaired the Law Department of the American University in Cairo. Professor Thomas serves on the U.S. State Department’s Advisory Council on International Law, and is a Counsellor of the American Society of Interna- tional Law. She has consulted for the USAID Bureau for Democracy, Conflict, and Humanitarian Affairs, and before entering the legal academy practiced international financial law at Shearman & Sterling’s New York offices. She has published widely on the relationship between international law, political economy, and global social justice in a variety of contexts. Professor Thomas earned her law degree from Harvard University and her bachelor’s degree from McGill University. David M. Trubek is Voss-Bascom Professor of Law and Dean of Internation- al Studies Emeritus at the University of Wisconsin–Madison and Senior Re- search Fellow at the Harvard Law School. He served as director of the UW’s Institute for Legal Studies from 1985 to 1990 and was appointed as University Dean of International Studies in 1990. In 1995 he became the founding direc- tor of the UW-Madison International Institute. A pioneer in the field of law and development, his work includes Law and the New Developmental State: The Brazilian Experience in Latin American Perspective (forthcoming, 2013), Direito, Planejamento e Desenvolvimento do Mercado de Capitais Brasileiro 1965-70 (2nd edition 2011), and The New Law and Economic Development: A Critical Appraisal (2006). Currently, he serves as Principal Investigator of LANDS, the project on Law and the New Developmental State and Co-Director of GLEE, the Project on Globalization, Lawyers, and Emerging Economies. Sarah Twigg is a consultant in the World Bank Gender and Development Unit. In her current role she conducts research on areas related to gender equality issues in laws and policy, and supports communications, outreach, and advo- cacy efforts in support of the World Bank’s gender and development priori- ties. Prior to joining the World Bank she worked as a researcher for two global Human Development Reports (2010 and 2011) published by the United Nations Development Programme, and as a gender and climate finance consultant for UN Women. Ms. Twigg also has experience practicing as a commercial lawyer in New Zealand and New York. Ms. Twigg holds a master’s degree in Interna- tional Politics and Business from New York University and bachelor’s degrees in Law and Political Science from the University of Otago, New Zealand. Roy F. Waldron is Senior Vice President, Associate General Counsel, and Chief Intellectual Property Counsel at Pfizer Inc., where he leads the team of attorneys and professionals who procure patents; works closely with R&D, Business Development, and the Pfizer Business Units; and ensures enforce- ment of trademarks. He represents Pfizer on the committees of various in- dustry organizations, including the International Federation of Pharmaceu- tical Manufacturers and Associations, where he is chair of the International IP and Trade Committee; the Pharmaceutical Research and Manufacturers of America, IPO, where he represents Pfizer on the Board of Directors; and INTERPAT. Mr. Waldron joined Pfizer in 1999 from White & Case’s IP practice group, and was previously an associate at Fish & Neave. He has a J.D. from Contributorsxxii New York University School of Law, a Ph.D. from Yale University (physical- organic chemistry), and a B.A. from Dartmouth College (chemistry). He was a DAAD Scholar at the Albrecht-Ludwigs-Universität in Freiburg, Germany, and a JSPS Post-Doctoral Fellow at Kyoto University in Japan. Chenguang Wang is Professor of Law and Director of the Health Law Re- search Center at Tsinghua University. He taught at Peking University Law School and Hong Kong City University Law School before joining Tsinghua in 2000. He has also taught as a visiting professor at the law schools of New York University, Cornell University, the University of Toronto, and the University of Pennsylvania. He has been a Special Adviser to the Supreme People’s Court since 2003, an arbitrator at the China International Economic and Trade Arbi- tration Commission since 1993, and a Deputy Chair of the China Association of Legal Theory (since 2003), the China Association of Legal Education (since 2007), and the China Health Law Association (since 2007). His teaching fo- cuses on legal theory, comparative law, and health law. He is the Co-Editor of China’s Journey toward the Rule of Law: Legal Reform, 1978–2008, and has pub- lished more than 40 scholarly articles on topics such as judicial system, legal education, comparative law and heath law. He received a B.A. (1980), M.A. (1983), and Ph.D. in Law (1999) from Peking University, and an LL.M. (1996) from Harvard University Law School. Zhenmin Wang is Professor of Law and Dean at the Tsinghua University School of Law and Vice President of the China Association of Constitutional Law. He is a member of the Committee for the Macao Basic Law and the Committee for the Hong Kong Basic Law under the Standing Committee of the Chinese National People’s Congress. In 2007, he was elected Deputy to the 13th Beijing City People’s Congress. He is the author of The Central-Special Administrative Region Relationship in China: From a Legal Perspective (2002) and Constitutional Review in China (2004). Professor Wang has published over 60 articles and presented papers at many regional and international conferences on Chinese constitutional law and legal reform. He is a Member of the Forum of Young Global Leaders of the World Economic Forum. Dean Wang received an LL.B. from Zhengzhou University (1989) and an LL.M. and Ph.D. in Law from People’s University of China (1992 and 1995, respectively). He also stud- ied in the Law Faculty of Hong Kong University from 1993 to 1995. He was a Fulbright Visiting Scholar at Harvard Law School in 2000–2001. Contributors xxiii The World Bank Legal Review Volume 4 Legal Innovation and Empowerment for Development Empowerment and Innovation Strategies for Law, Justice, and Development Chantal thomas The concept of the rule of law has now garnered near-universal recognition both as a means and as an end of socioeconomic improvement in poor coun- tries. Yet, the very universality of the concept has generated next-level prob- lems. The rule of law as an abstract goal offers little guidance about the practi- cal aspects of such a goal in specific contexts. As Hassane Cissé notes in this volume, “[d]evelopment policymakers have learnt through bitter experience that a uniform, one-size-fits-all approach to policy interventions in poor coun- tries can have unfortunate, indeed disastrous, consequences.”1 The challenge for rule of law reformers, then, is to overcome the pitfalls of a one-size-fits-all approach and instead to devise regulatory strategies suitable and responsive to the local environment. An additional challenge for rule of law and related “good governance” reforms is that the economic liberalization programs accompanying such policies often have failed to address social inequities and hierarchies. Some contemporary development policy analysts have focused on how to incor- porate these social goals. For example, Amartya Sen’s Development as Freedom provides a template for understanding how the fulfillment of civil, political, and social rights could be factored into development policy.2 The challenge is to ensure that opportunities for, and benefits of, prosperity are equitably enjoyed, and that the least advantaged are able to share them. Both of these challenges—transposing policies to particular contexts and ensuring more equitable processes and outcomes of policy reform—inspire the theme of this volume: Legal Innovation and Empowerment for Development. The fourth installment of a research effort under way at the World Bank, this volume highlights both the necessity of innovating law and policy to address specific development contexts and the importance of doing so in a way that will contribute to socioeconomic empowerment. In this way, the volume makes the case that legal innovation can drive, rather than simply reflect, em- powerment and development. The theme of legal innovation and empowerment for development com- plements substantive and institutional sensibilities in current development policy. Substantively, development policy discourse seems to have moved away from tacking hard toward statist policy or neoliberal policy. Rather, 1 See, in this volume, Hassane Cissé, Legal Empowerment of the Poor: Past, Present, Future. 2 Amartya Sen, Development as Freedom (Oxford U. Press 1999). 3 The World Bank Legal Review4 something of a more self-consciously moderate approach is emerging in which the basic commitment to market-oriented regulation is affirmed, but the im- portance of meeting social needs as a concurrent rather than a long-term goal is simultaneously recognized.3 Institutionally, this self-styled pragmatism is reflected through the en- dorsement of “new governance” techniques that blend public sector and pri- vate sector approaches. Public-private partnerships constitute one important example, but there are many variations, such as a bottom-line approach to measuring policy effects that resembles market metrics. There is cause for hope that these new approaches may help balance out some of the excesses of prior eras. They may be reflected in a greater focus on locality, as well as a greater focus on inclusiveness in processes of gover- nance. Equally welcome is the greater awareness of the importance of self- assessment by the range of actors who participate in the development policy cosmos: developed-country governments, international organizations, and nongovernmental organizations (NGOs). Still, one might ask how much of this apparent change remains only sur- face deep. Can these reforms transform deeply entrenched policy orientations on the ground? Is the turn to social innovation and empowerment merely cos- metic, leaving underlying structural dynamics and biases intact? How pos- sible is genuine interdisciplinary exchange among the various categories of experts in law, economics, and public policy? There is much evidence that deep institutional “inefficiencies” remain. Key among these are imperfect in- formation, powerful interests, and subjective models.4 Despite these persistent questions, many new developments in the field are promising and interesting, and some of these are presented in this volume. In exploring contemporary examples of legal innovation and empowerment, the volume offers a variety of focal points. Some chapters focus on elaborating the broad concepts of innovation and empowerment. Others focus on govern- mental innovations in particular country contexts. Still others discuss the role of NGOs and civil society. Finally, some chapters describe emerging trends in international laws and organizations. Although this brief introduction cannot do justice to the richness and complexity of these contributions, it does con- sider each focal point in turn. The Conceptual State of Play What precisely is meant by “legal innovation” and “legal empowerment”? The general issue of legal, judicial, and constitutional innovation is addressed 3 See, in this volume, David M. Trubek, Diogo R. Coutinho, & Mario G. Schapiro, Toward a New Law and Development: New State Activism in Brazil and the Challenge for Legal Institutions. 4 Chantal Thomas, Law and Neoclassical Economic Development: Toward an Institutionalist Critique of Institutionalism, 96 Cornell L. Rev. 968, 1018–1023 (2011). Empowerment and Innovation Strategies for Law, Justice, and Development 5 by Sam Muller and Maurits Barendrecht in “The Justice Innovation Approach: How Justice Sector Leaders in Development Contexts Can Promote Innova- tion.” The authors stress competition among potential providers (alternative dispute resolution is envisioned as a potential competitor to traditional judi- cial processes) as well as a redefinition of members of society as stakeholders. Within this framework, Muller and Barendrecht emphasize a few key as- pects of desirable “justice innovation.” First, it is low cost and bottom up. Sec- ond, it emphasizes that even though policy goals should be clear, the factors leading to their realization will inevitably be complex, reflecting the environ- ment on the ground. Third, this version of justice innovation favors public- private partnerships in the delivery of access to justice, including something like a “Build-Operate-Transfer” model (in which investors are permitted to build and operate a firm for a period of time in exchange for, among other things, an agreement to transfer possession eventually to the owner). Finally, this version emphasizes the importance of protecting and rewarding innova- tion and experimentation. The authors offer a pragmatic approach to the question of how to deliver a public good, such as justice, through a model based on the ideal of private sector competition. Such an approach may have the virtue of encouraging clearer quantification and greater accountability through a “marketized” fo- cus on systemic “profits,” in the form of increased satisfaction with access to justice, which might permit more precise measurement of the “deliverables” of reform. At the same time, some implications of competition in the justice sector remain unclear. For example, if competition leads to the proliferation of dispute resolution fora, will the “forum shopping” that likely ensues improve the justice sector through regulatory competition, or encourage negative ex- ternalities (i.e., gaming the system)? More profoundly, what danger might privatizing justice pose to public policy goals? As for legal empowerment, this concept is taken up in Hassane Cissé in “Legal Empowerment of the Poor: Past, Present, Future.” Now that the “idea that law has an important role to play in promoting economic development has become well established,” Cissé notes that the “traditional focus on in- stitutions and government machinery has been widened to bring the people themselves into view.” Legal empowerment of the poor (LEP) is in part a reaction to classical rule of law approaches, which focus too much on “institutions and state struc- tures,” perhaps with the unstated premise that these automatically benefit the poor, rather than on whether such benefits are quantifiably delivered. Cissé emphasizes the point made by Muller and Barendrecht that earlier approach- es have been overly top down and therefore likely to misapprehend the con- text of those on the lower rungs of society. Despite these improvements, Cissé notes some difficulties with LEP. First, there is the problem of “causality versus correlation” that characterizes the entire field of good governance policy—does economic empowerment result The World Bank Legal Review6 from, or lead to, better institutions? Second, there is the delicate matter of compliance of LEP reforms with the World Bank Articles of Agreement, which prohibit interference in political matters. Third, in the form it has taken up to now, most visibly in the Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor (CLEP), LEP has come under criticism for overestimating the impact of legal exclusion as opposed to other factors on poverty and adopting neoliberal eco- nomic assumptions. Among the latter, property rights enforcement is “pos- sibly the most contested” on the CLEP agenda. Beyond these conceptual difficulties, there are some applied challenges in implementing LEP policy. Cissé writes of the need to see LEP as not merely a technocratic strategy, but also as one that entails confronting the reality of en- trenched power elites and interests. Additionally, vigilance against one-size- fits-all policies must continue. Examples of local LEP solutions include greater incorporation of informal justice systems. If the perils of one-size-fits-all are to be taken seriously, then general ideas about legal empowerment and innovation must take into context more spe- cific social hierarchies. A useful intervention in thinking through one kind of particularity—gender equality—is offered by Jeni Klugman and Sarah Twigg in “The Role of Laws and Institutions in Expanding Women’s Voice, Agency, and Empowerment.” As these authors point out, gender equality has now been mainstreamed as a focus of development policy, one example of which is the 2012 World Development Report, whose title is Gender Equality and Development. A focus on gender equality encourages analytically productive atten- tion to the effects of law. The authors focus in part on formally unequal rules, pointing out that although more and more countries have incorporated non- discrimination principles into their basic laws, many “still have legal provi- sions that overtly discriminate against women in both formal statutory and customary law.” These formal inequalities affect, among other things, access by women to entrepreneurial opportunity through restriction of their ability to sign contracts, open bank accounts, and undertake other business activities. A gender equality analysis requires looking at whether the laws apply for- mally unequal rules as well as at whether they enforce a regulatory structure that is conducive to the kind of economic growth that would increase the well- being of women (and, by extension, children and households more generally). For example, family law can enforce differential treatment, as in the case of many inheritance laws. It can also enforce seemingly neutral provisions that nevertheless generate a disparate adverse impact on women. The authors give an example of the latter when discussing the failure of some legal systems to provide for joint ownership in marriage. The potentially disparate effects of titling practices point to the impor- tance of understanding context before adopting prescribed LEP reforms such as property registration. Without understanding the existing legal and eco- nomic distribution of resources, such registration might have the effect of dis- Empowerment and Innovation Strategies for Law, Justice, and Development 7 owning less powerful members of a community. The authors describe one project, the Reconstruction of Aceh Land Administration System, which ad- dressed this issue by introducing land registration and creating joint titling at the same time—a significant social intervention. Such examples suggest the importance of context within the more specific category of gender. Country Contexts Further to the centrality of context in shaping development policy, the volume considers a variety of country studies. Among the most innovative in the field have been the emerging developing country economies. Brazil and China are leaders within these ranks, and this volume offers multiple perspectives on each country. China In “Legal Transplantation and Legal Development in Transitional China,” Chenguang Wang takes on the debate about the benefits of legal transplants in the specific context of China. Wang notes that transplantation should not be viewed as exceptional: every legal system has evolved through reference to others. Yet, transplants are vulnerable to several critiques. Synthesizing these two sides of the debate, he offers a view of transplants that seeks to capture their benefits while minimizing their potential harms. As Wang demonstrates, China in the past several years has boldly ad- opted numerous legal transplants, but with two innovative characteristics that have increased the chances for success. First, policy makers have integrated transplanted laws with “aboriginal” laws. Second, transplants have involved selective, as opposed to wholesale, adoption. In “Achieving Development through Innovative Constitutionalism: A China Story,” Zhenmin Wang and Yuan Tao tell a story that bears out Chenguang Wang’s narrative of incremental transplantation. Wang and Tao de- scribe the gradual and piecemeal reform of China’s constitution from socialist legal and political commitments to the constitutionalism of liberal capitalist economies. They argue that this style of reform has contributed significantly to China’s economic rise. Regardless of actual causality, these reforms form an important part of the larger legal picture. In “Rule of Law as a Watermark: China’s Legal and Judicial Challenges,” Stéphanie Balme, looks beyond China’s constitution to its massive adoption, from the late 1970s onward, of new legislation and administrative regula- tions—an exertion she dubs “quantitative legislative reforms.” These reforms coincided with the adoption of the 1982 constitution, and, in many cases, provided processes for redressing grievances that were admin- istrative rather than judicial, such as the proliferation of xinfang offices. Balme suggests that China’s process of legalization is incomplete and ongoing. This process is evidenced by, among other things, a gradual increase in both formal The World Bank Legal Review8 legal and nonlegal mediation disputes over xinfang complaints; improvement of the legal system’s “hardware” through better education and regulation of the legal profession and judicial system; and increased incorporation of hu- man rights discourse. Among the remaining challenges are the legal guarantee of ownership rights, which suffers because the current system is complex and the judicial system does not have clear authority to regulate. Underlying all this is the fact that, even though the adoption of the new constitution precipitated much of this reform, there continues to be a lack of respect for the constitution . . . explained by the de facto absence of a hierarchy of norms (despite a clear definition of the “sources of the law,” [fa yuan]), resulting in confusion both in the or- ganization and in the legal texts, administrative regulations, and de- crees. It can also be explained by the lack of a clear conception of the position of the constitution in the hierarchy of the normative system. The chapters by Balme and Wang and Tao support Chenguang Wang’s general analysis of the piecemeal and partial nature of legal transplantation and reform in China. This process leaves much to be desired. At the same time, one might see the disorganized quality of legal reform in China as an acceptable price for a greater legitimacy borne of incremental change as op- posed to radical transplantation. Brazil As with China and its adoption of a new constitution in 1982, the adoption of a new constitution in 1988 marked a watershed moment in the transforma- tion of the structure of economic law and regulation for Brazil. In “Toward a New Law and Development: New State Activism in Brazil and the Chal- lenge for Legal Institutions,” David M. Trubek, Diogo R. Coutinho, and Mario G. Schapiro identify a resulting new wave of governance that seeks to avoid perceived extremes of prior eras in development policy in Brazil—both the unrelenting statism of the early decolonization period and the adamantly deregulatory orientation of the Washington Consensus. Although Brazil’s government adopted characteristic policies in both eras, by the late 1980s, the country was beginning to move toward the ap- proach that Trubek et al. deem “new state activism.” Beginning with the 1988 constitution, building through the Cardoso administration of the mid-1990s, and maturing after the 2002 election of Lula da Silva, new state activism em- braces innovation in governance in two respects. First, innovation as an end is encouraged, particularly in industrial policy. Specialized measures designed to boost select market sectors have been adopted successfully over objections that “governments were not able to strategically identify targets.” Second, in- novation characterizes the means by which policies are implemented. In par- ticular, new state activism features partnerships between the government and the private sector that improve capacity on both sides. Empowerment and Innovation Strategies for Law, Justice, and Development 9 The authors describe a series of structural conditioning factors that have driven innovation in these various manifestations. Legal protections for prop- erty rights and against expropriation, arising from domestic constitutional law and from international treaty commitments, arguably forced the Lula admin- istration to pursue social policy goals through new techniques that ultimately were friendlier to both domestic and foreign investors. The innovative approach to governance that Trubek et al. describe is fur- ther detailed in the context of environmental and water law by Luciano Badini and Luciano Alvarenga in “The Role of the Public Ministry in the Defense of the Environment: Hydrogeographical Regions and Attitudes for Coping with Socioenvironmental Conflicts.” Badini and Alvarenga focus on the techniques that the Brazilian Public Ministry has used to achieve environmental protec- tion and conservation objectives related to freshwater. The authors begin by noting that the Public Ministry is a product of the 1988 constitution, and as such exemplifies that document’s combination of ambitious social goals and institutional prudentialism, as described in Tru- bek et al. Badini and Alvarenga then discuss the particular strategies adopted in relation to freshwater regulation: first, the reorganization of the territorial objects of regulation from a fragmented scheme to one based on the drainage basin as the basic unit of analysis; and second, the pursuit of nonjudicial and therefore presumably less costly approaches to conflict resolution. In the cases of both Brazil and China, we see the operation of the prag- matic and synthetic approaches that are also invoked in more general form in the discussions of Muller and Barendrecht and of Cissé. In both countries, successful reform policies arose out of careful attention to context and a com- paratively gradual pace. Concessions were made to external and internal con- straints of legal and economic liberalism, but socially transformative goals were no less vigorously pursued. A comparative reading of these chapters highlights a notable difference between the two countries: whereas in Brazil the overarching focus of socially transformative policies appears to have been direct poverty-reduction measures, in the Chinese context, more traditional economic growth has remained a priority; and although these measures are also achieving poverty reduction, they may do so at the immediate (though increasingly contested) expense of the environment and the displacement of socially marginal populations. The Global North Within good governance policy, anticorruption efforts play a major role in supporting rule of law reform. The legal innovations discussed by Rita Adam in “Innovation in Asset Recovery: The Swiss Perspective” and Karyn Kenny in “International Asset Sharing: A Multipurpose Tool for Development” point to the beginnings of an important trend in anticorruption policy—one in which developed countries interrogate their own legal systems to identify and cor- rect connections to theft of public assets in poor countries. The complicity of financial institutions and legal systems in the global north contributes to these The World Bank Legal Review10 broader enabling conditions. The temptation of financial corruption in poor countries is magnified by the ability to secure ill-gotten gains in legal jurisdic- tions out of the reach of local actors. Adam describes legal reforms in Switzerland that allow the Swiss Federal Council to freeze assets reasonably suspected to be the product of public theft and to repatriate those assets to the home country without the cooperation of either the home country government (which, Adam argues, may be too weak and ineffective to mount an effective request) or local prosecutorial au- thorities. Kenny describes multilateral, bilateral, and unilateral arrangements to share assets among countries when those assets constitute the proceeds of crime that implicates multiple jurisdictions, such as drug trafficking or money laundering. Much of the contemporary global anticorruption campaign has been ham- pered by a failure to realize that corruption in poor countries arises not only from local malfeasance, but also from enabling conditions across borders and within a globalized political economy. Both Adam and Kenny describe inno- vations that have disrupted and minimized the perverse incentives that for- eign jurisdictions offer to commit corruption. NGOs and Civil Society Whereas the chapters described above focus on governmental reforms, others in this volume take on the role of NGOs and civil society in pursuing legal in- novation and legal empowerment. In “The Political Economy of Improving Traditional Justice Systems: A Case Study of NGO Engagement with Shalish in Bangladesh,” Stephen Golub examines the advantages and disadvantages of employing traditional and customary forms of dispute resolution such as shalish. The advantages, ac- cording to Golub, include increased effectiveness due to greater legitimacy and lower user and operational costs. The disadvantages include unwieldi- ness and unpredictability, as well as reinforcement of traditional hierarchies such as gender inequality. Golub describes how NGOs have worked to modify traditional shalish so as to address some of the disadvantages. In so doing, these NGOs are taking an innovative approach to the goal of increasing access to justice. Rather than replacing traditional justice with a legal transplant, they are seeking to adapt tradition to contemporary concerns while retaining institutional advantages. At the same time, extensive NGO involvement can raise questions of account- ability or neutrality in influencing the outcomes of disputes. Moreover, efforts to correct ingrained social prejudices may fail, resulting in their inadvertent retrenchment. Golub concludes by recommending a cautious optimism with respect to shalish but also emphasizes the need for further study, not only of shalish, but also of other fora for alternative dispute resolution. Empowerment and Innovation Strategies for Law, Justice, and Development 11 In “‘We Want What the OK Tedi Women Have!’ Guidance from Papua New Guinea on Women’s Engagement in Mining Deals,” Nicholas Menzies and Georgia Harley tell the story of a mining agreement negotiation in Papua New Guinea in which some participants in the negotiations represented wom- en as a community group. These interests were not represented by a formally constituted NGO, but rather more informally in the sense of women repre- senting a significant group in civil society. The participation of women in the OK Tedi negotiations is a promising ex- ample of bringing civil society to the table and more generally of recognizing the interests of noncorporate stakeholders in investment. Menzies and Harley identify specific characteristics that allowed the women representatives to ne- gotiate successfully—most important, the experience and skills of the negotia- tors themselves. Yet, the various benefits that were negotiated have suffered from spotty implementation. Once the agreement was concluded, the national govern- ment of Papua New Guinea failed to take an interest in implementing the measures it called for, and the negotiators left the scene, leaving the communi- ty ill-equipped to attend to implementation. This points to some of the struc- tural disadvantages of bringing civil society or the community in as a separate group in the formation of large foreign investment agreements. Although the “community development” aspects of the agreement represented a laudable innovation on the standard foreign direct investment model inspired by the goal of empowerment, further innovation in implementation will be required to realize this goal more fully. Multilateral Contexts Particularly in this age of globalization, the regulatory environment in most countries is significantly shaped by the values and practices of international legal regimes and organizations. These domains of international law extend across a range of subject matters, from human rights to finance. Innovations in this area involve creating stronger connections between the goals of particular specialized regimes. In “Human Rights and Development: Regime Interaction and the Fragmentation of International Law,” Siobhán McInerney-Lankford speaks to this question. Her chapter begins with a gen- eral observation of the phenomenon of fragmentation in international law and a demonstration of fragmentation in regards to human rights law and devel- opment law. Institutionally, these fields remain largely separate. McInerney-Lankford argues, however, that there is also an increasing convergence between human rights and development. Substantively, this con- vergence arises in “shared principles such as equality, participation, account- ability, transparency, and voice, as well as in attention to vulnerable groups.” These policies are acknowledged by international organizations from the United Nations to the International Finance Corporation. The World Bank Legal Review12 However, “not all such provisions translate into a reliance on human rights in a direct operational sense.” McInerney-Lankford points to region- al systems, particularly those in Europe, that intertwine human rights and development more extensively. For example, the European Union formally incorporates human rights principles in its economic partnerships with non- European countries. Such integration, McInerney-Lankford believes, should be more broadly adopted. In this way, she calls for regime interaction as both an innovation and an empowerment strategy. Ideally, international law will eventually consist of “human rights as a shared legal framework, highlighting both partner and donor obligations under international human rights law and of- fering concrete operational entry points for their application in development activities.” In “Beyond the Orthodoxy of Rule of Law and Justice Sector Reform: A Framework for Legal Empowerment and Innovation through the Conven- tion on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities,” Janet E. Lord, Deepti Samant Raja, and Peter Blanck show how this convention—one of the newer ad- ditions to the United Nations’ “core” human rights treaties—innovates by establishing extensive guidelines for domestic implementation of the trea- ty’s principles. In “Transforming through Transparency: Opening Up the World Bank’s Sanctions Regime,” Conrad C. Daly and Frank A. Fariello, Jr., describe the Bank’s sanctions regime, which was established in 1996 to combat corruption and fraud in the disbursement of funds. The regime forms part of a greater ef- fort by the Bank to increase accountability and transparency in its operations, and stands alongside better-known innovations of the Bank such as its Inspec- tion Panel, which examines compliance with Bank protocols more broadly. Such reforms represent commendable efforts to bring good governance policy home; that is, to prioritize good governance principles not only in bor- rower countries but also in the Bank’s own institutional practices. One ques- tion that emerges in considering these reforms is why the Inspection Panel and the sanctions regime are separate institutions. It seems debatable whether the reasons for such separation extend beyond mere historical contingency. As these kinds of internal reforms develop, perhaps the Bank will integrate and consolidate its various monitoring functions. In “Intellectual Property: Facilitating Technology Transfer for Develop- ment,” Roy F. Waldron discusses the innovative arrangements that phar- maceutical companies are entering into with public sector actors in order to increase access to medicines, framed by the author as the transfer and applica- tion of medical technology to national public health. Such innovations are directly linked to empowerment in that they may allow developing countries to increase levels of public health in vulnerable populations and in society more generally. Although many of the specific de- tails of these agreements are not discussed for reasons of confidentiality, they Empowerment and Innovation Strategies for Law, Justice, and Development 13 appear to be highly promising responses to the problem of access to medi- cines, in which the research and development prowess of pharmaceutical companies can be harnessed by nonprofit organizations with public health as their main priority. These arrangements involve a number of different types of international organizations, including the World Intellectual Property Organization (WIPO), the Joint United Nations Programme on HIV/AIDS (UNAIDS), and the World Health Organization (WHO). These organizations often take leading roles in these arrangements, as do other nonprofit and research organizations such as the Oswaldo Cruz Foundation in Brazil and the Geneva-based Drugs for Neglected Diseases Initiative. Furthermore, these initiatives take place against the backdrop of inter- national economic law established by the World Trade Organization (WTO) Agreement on Trade-Related Intellectual Property Rights (TRIPS). Since the adoption of TRIPS, the WTO membership has taken several strides to clarify that the more stringent patent-protection rules in TRIPS should not apply to many developing country access-to-medicine issues.5 These developments in international intellectual property rules have re- arranged the leverage of the parties Waldron describes in his chapter. These parties are “bargaining in the shadow of the law”6—in this case, TRIPS law. Thus, although it is true that, as Waldron points out, pharmaceutical compa- nies are willing to engage in these technology transfer agreements only be- cause patent-protection rules are in place, willingness is likely enhanced by the emergence of legally valid exceptions to those rules. In other words, these companies have an incentive to reach voluntary agreements rather than be subjected to the compulsory licensing permitted by the TRIPS exceptions. In “OHADA Nears the Twenty-Year Mark: An Assessment,” Renaud Beauchard looks at the regional context of the Organization for the Harmoni- zation of Business Law in Africa (OHADA). An ambitious integration scheme, OHADA represents a step forward for the region in terms of the recognition of the benefits of intraregional trade. At the same time, OHADA bears signs of adverse side effects of legal transplantation. Considering the chapters on China presented in this volume, a comparison between modes of transplan- tation is perhaps instructive. Whereas China’s transplants were relatively piecemeal, OHADA constituted a major and sudden overhaul involving some elements that were not particularly useful in the local context, such as a bankruptcy act. Whereas China’s reforms integrated aboriginal practices, OHADA’s seemed to ignore local practices and instead emphasized uniformity and conformity with national and international standards. 5 WTO Declaration on TRIPS and Public Health, WT/MIN(01)/DEC/2 (Nov. 20, 2001), which was followed by the Decision on the Implementation of Paragraph 6 of the Doha Declaration on the TRIPS Agreement and Public Health, WT/L/540 (Sep. 2, 2003). 6 Robert H. Mnookin & Lewis Kornhauser, Bargaining in the Shadow of the Law, 88 Yale L. J. 950 (1979). The World Bank Legal Review14 For example, the author discusses the difficulty in convincing local actors to settle transactional matters according to OHADA law: they observe that the complex structure of local markets in the central location of Cotonou “op- erates almost entirely outside the realm of formal law and ignores OHADA.” Although some efficiencies are probably be gained by coming into compli- ance with OHADA, the possibility of competing efficiencies of local practices and “private ordering”7 appear to have been wholly dismissed, creating the danger that OHADA will cause greater disruption than improvement of re- gional markets. Given these difficulties, the history recounted in Marc Frilet’s “Legal In- novation for Development: The OHADA Experience” is instructive. Frilet explains that OHADA drafters sought to correct deficiencies in business law practices in the newly independent francophone African countries. Because of difficulty in ascertaining applicable principles of local law, and other in- formation and capacity asymmetries, Frilet states, French law firms servicing local clients tended to provide “authoritative interpretations” based on the company law of their home country. Although this practice may have served as a useful stopgap measure in the early days of independence, the need for a clearer and more locally accessible legal framework inspired the efforts that culminated in OHADA. Thus, the reasoning behind OHADA was largely sound. The member countries stood to capture efficiency gains through legal harmonization that could spur much-needed regional growth. Moreover, the initiative and par- ticipation of distinguished experts and regional authorities to achieve this objective was commendable. As Frilet notes, however, both the substantive and the institutional realization of OHADA’s objectives remain incomplete. Substantively, the framework does not address topics that Frilet asserts are crucially important to current development strategies, such as public contract law. Institutionally, OHADA continues to struggle with implementation, both for reasons of capacity and because the framework is not yet widely under- stood by or familiar to local actors. Consequently, the “OHADA experience” offers insights into what kinds of innovative approaches are likely to be successful. Perhaps a more wide- ly consultative and participatory process could have yielded a more readily adaptive legal framework. In addition, OHADA reinforces the critical need for institutional and administrative capacity to implement legal innovations once adopted. At the same time, such recommendations come with a num- ber of challenges. OHADA drafters may have avoided wider consultation for fear that it would slow or stop momentum. And the devotion of scarce insti- tutional resources to the ambitious goals of OHADA requires costly choices both economically and politically. OHADA exemplifies both the appeal and the pitfalls of legal innovation strategies. 7 Melvin A. Eisenberg, Private Ordering through Negotiation: Dispute-Settlement and Rulemaking, 89 Harv. L. Rev. 637 (1976). Empowerment and Innovation Strategies for Law, Justice, and Development 15 Conclusion This volume reflects the interconnected roles that actors in development policy—governments, donors, lenders, investors, and civil society—play in shaping the substance and the effect of legal reforms. Legal innovation and empowerment for development recognizes and responds to this interdepen- dence. The analytics of attentiveness to context, participatory decision mak- ing, and systemic institutional assessment that emerge from these studies offer valuable contributions to the ongoing effort to revitalize contemporary approaches to law, equity, and global justice. 17 The Justice Innovation Approach How Justice Sector Leaders in Development Contexts Can Promote Innovation Sam muller and mauritS Barendrecht In September 2012, the UN General Assembly devoted its opening debate to the rule of law.1 A clearer signal that the community of states attaches great importance to the development of the rule of law is hardly imaginable. In De- livering Justice: Programme of Action to Strengthen the Rule of Law at the National and International Levels, the secretary-general of the United Nations proposed a program called “delivering justice.” According to this report, the rule of law involves more than the state and its institutions: it “is at the heart of the social contract between the State and individuals under its jurisdiction, and ensures that justice permeates at every level.” The report continues: “responsibility for ensuring rule of law . . . lies with member States and their citizens.”2 Clearly, the rule of law is about more than simply setting rules; it also involves mecha- nisms to ensure that rules and dispute-resolution processes actually work. De- livering Justice contains sections about budgeting and planning, accountable and transparent delivery at the national level, monitoring, the role of civil society, and informal and traditional justice systems. Rather than encourag- ing states to enact more laws or ensuring that new rights are protected, the secretary-general proposes that states set goals for ensuring the rule of law, assume a monitoring role, measure effectiveness, perform benchmarking ex- ercises, and report progress against indicators. In sum, the report encourages state actors to rethink their role in delivering justice. This chapter develops this idea further. It shows how justice sector lead- ers—ministers of justice, secretaries-general of ministries, strategy depart- ments of ministries, chief justices, and directors of public prosecution agen- cies—can help society deliver justice rather than simply providing justice themselves. The chapter assumes that the process of delivering justice can be improved in a way similar to the delivery of health care, education, or electricity: through continuous innovation. It addresses the issue of how justice sector leaders can enable effective justice innovation. 1 See UN General Assembly Resolution A/Res/66/102 (Jan. 13, 2012), available at http:// www.unrol.org/files/GA%20Resolution%202012.pdf, paragraph 15 et seq. 2 See Delivering Justice: Programme of Action to Strengthen the Rule of Law at the National and International Levels, Report of the Secretary-General 2, 6–8 (Mar. 16, 2012). http://www.unrol.org/files/GA%20Resolution%202012.pdf http://www.unrol.org/files/GA%20Resolution%202012.pdf The World Bank Legal Review18 The analysis is written with the development context in mind. However, the suggested approach is relevant for all countries, albeit with different pri- orities and areas of emphasis. This chapter first explains the meaning of justice innovation. Then it sets out what a strategic justice leader can do to stimulate and consolidate rule of law. The chapter ends by explaining exactly why the justice innovation approach is worth pursuing and how it can help deal with a number of challenges. What Is Justice Innovation? Building on the Wikipedia definition, we say that justice innovation is the effort to create better or more effective justice products, processes, services, technol- ogies, or ideas that are accepted by markets, governments, and society. Two concepts stand out in this definition: the emphasis on better or more effective justice products and the need to ensure that these products are actually used and liked by all stakeholders. Rule of law assistance and justice sector budgets tend to fund the build- ing or strengthening of existing state institutions. The image of basic rule of law institutions has not changed much in the past 200 years. Courts, bar as- sociations, law-making procedures, and parliaments are all founded on ideas developed during a period in Western history when empires and kings were being replaced by states and democracies. Until recently, justice sector leaders and the organizations that supply development funds felt responsible for train- ing and resourcing judges, prosecutors, and police officers; building bar asso- ciations and national councils for the judiciary; developing constitutions and other laws modeled on Western standards; and setting up national gazettes in which to publish the laws. However, most rule of law mechanisms emerged independent of state in- stitutions. Informal justice systems—with communication, negotiation, me- diation, and adjudication—tend to develop whenever groups of people live or work together and conflicts must be managed.3 Protection of property rights is triggered by demand when people start investing in assets of a certain value that become scarce.4 Often, the state incorporates successful innovations that were developed privately. In line with this reality, and taking criminal justice as an example, the question at the core of the justice innovation approach should be not “how do 3 Deborah Isser ed., Customary Justice and Rule of Law in War Torn Societies (United States Insti- tute of Peace Press 2011). 4 See Francis Fukuyama, The Origins of Political Order, from Prehuman Times to the French Revo- lution 247 (Farrar, Straus and Giroux 2011) (“Of all the components of contemporary states, effective legal institutions are perhaps the most difficult to construct”); Lee J. Alston & Ber- nardo Mueller, Property Rights and the State, in Claude Ménard & Mary M. Shirley, Handbook of New Institutional Economics 573 (Springer Verlag 2008). The Justice Innovation Approach 19 we build a good prosecution service?” but rather “how do we empower and stimulate the stakeholders in the criminal justice system—judges, prosecu- tors, police officers, victim support services, civil servants, legal aid lawyers, psychologists working with drug offenders, academics, correction services, and social entrepreneurs—to continuously improve criminal justice mecha- nisms?” In other words, how can strategic justice leaders contribute to the innovation process so that more justice is delivered? What Can Justice Sector Leaders Do to Foster Innovation? The literature on innovation shows that successful innovation processes can- not be forced by following a simple set of prescriptions. Innovation is a matter of doing many things well and involves many factors.5 One survey found no less than 40 factors associated with successful innovation.6 Many are related to what happens on the ground, as justice sector professionals improve their processes step by step and through trial and error. But there are quite a few things that justice sector leaders can do to help justice innovation thrive.7 Generate Possibilities In the innovation initiation phase, the literature lists nine factors associated with innovation. Innovation is stimulated by creating a setting with diverse views, people, and backgrounds. Practitioners should focus on users of rule of law mechanisms and the people directly serving them. They know best what is needed and what might work. Time and space are required for innovation, as are clear goals for the innovation process. A justice sector leader can take several actions in this phase. Articulate a Clear Vision Innovation can be inspired by a clear vision that shows political commitment and a desire to redirect resources in a particular area. This is a critical factor because innovation—for instance, when dealing with employment conflicts— will require efforts from a wide variety of actors—for instance, employers, lawyers, trade unions, lawmakers, and courts. Typically, the organizations in the justice supply chain are independent and cannot be managed in one com- mon direction. They must be inspired, and they must see that others in the supply chain are adapting to change. 5 See The Best Story in Development, The Economist (May 19, 2012), available at http://www .economist.com/node/21555571, which cites a study of the many things that contribute to a significant drop in child mortality. 6 Nizar Becheikh, Réjéan Landry & Nabil Amara, Lessons from Innovation Empirical Studies in the Manufacturing Sector: A Systematic Review of the Literature from 1993–2003, 26 Technovation 644–64 (2006). 7 See the Innovation Model, available at http://www.innovatingjustice.com/innovationlab /innovation-assistance/innovation-model/?subcategoryID=15535, developed on the basis of factors that have been found to support innovation in the public sector. http://www.economist.com/node/21555571 http://www.economist.com/node/21555571 http://www.innovatingjustice.com/innovationlab/innovation-assistance/innovation-model/?subcategoryID=15535 http://www.innovatingjustice.com/innovationlab/innovation-assistance/innovation-model/?subcategoryID=15535 The World Bank Legal Review20 Politicians are subject to many pressures and can unknowingly sow con- fusion. A minister may make a speech one day in which he (or she) states that access to justice should be improved. The next day he might argue before a different audience that courts are overburdened and that people should do more to resolve their own conflicts. The visions of justice sector leaders should be realistic: in many postconflict contexts, donors demand the articulation of a national rule of law plan. (Interestingly, the donor states that demand such national rule of law plans rarely have one themselves.) Those plans are often very wide in scope (they are, after all, “national”), they rarely clearly priori- tize, and they often contain unrealistic timelines,8 making it hard for potential innovators to coalesce around a common agenda. To be realized, a vision must be as specific as possible, couched in plain language, ambitious but doable, and consistent, not changing with every new administration. The Millennium Development Goals are an excellent example of a clear, concrete, ambitious, doable, and consistent vision. Other examples of justice innovation visions are “to increase the number of people living on land and in houses with tenure security by 20 percent in the next year,” “to make a judge available to every village of more than 500 people within the next two years,” and “to ensure that employers and employees get a solu- tion within two months after filing a claim.” It would not be difficult to list a number of priorities for justice sector innovation based on an assessment of the most frequent and urgent justiciable problems the population experiences; such surveys have been done before.9 Break the Rules Innovation means doing things in new ways. The innovation literature urges innovators to challenge every rule of the game. For justice sector profession- als, this directive creates a dilemma, because their legitimacy is built on fol- lowing the rules, not breaking them. Changing procedures in a relevant way almost always requires a change in the rules or at least in the way rules are applied. So everywhere in the world, professional judges, lawyers, and oth- ers are more likely waiting for the rules to change than taking initiatives to improve procedures. Justice sector leaders can address this dilemma by allowing experiments, provided that the experiments are clearly motivated by goals such as decreas- ing costs, preventing error, increasing procedural justice, or speeding up 8 One of the more extreme examples is the Afghanistan Compact, agreed to between Afghani- stan and the international community, in London in 2006, which provides as benchmarks: “By end-2010, the legal framework required under the constitution, including civil, criminal and commercial law, will be put in place, distributed to all judicial and legislative institu- tions and made available to the public” and “By end-2010, functioning institutions of justice will be fully operational in each province of Afghanistan, and the average time to resolve contract disputes will be reduced as much as possible.” 9 See Basic Justice Care, available at http://www.hiil.org/publication/strategies-towards -basic-justice-care, which lists some basic justice needs. http://www.hiil.org/publication/strategies-towards-basic-justice-care http://www.hiil.org/publication/strategies-towards-basic-justice-care The Justice Innovation Approach 21 trials. Instead of stressing formal barriers to new solutions, justice sector lead- ers can urge stakeholders to develop, try, and test new procedures and to ask for changes in the rules if necessary. Procedures for experimental treatments in the health care sector may be a source of inspiration. Foster Competition Innovation is hardly conceivable without competition. Innovation in an envi- ronment like Silicon Valley is not based on monopolies and rigid agreements between players as to who will deliver what to the exclusion of others. Such incubators are messy, chaotic places where smart ideas compete with other smart ideas for funding, duplication is not frowned upon, and the shared as- sumption is that the best idea will win out in the end. What is “best” is mea- sured by sales figures, demand by clients, and the willingness of venture capi- talists to invest. Organization is limited: it is aimed at creating a place where innovators can meet other innovators and where people who are interested in funding start-ups can find the best ones. What happens next is thanks to the magic of the marketplace and innovation. Can this concept be transposed to the world of order, norms, and justice? Not if one perceives the delivery of justice as the application of a master pro- gram emanating from a state’s constitution. In the real world, delivering justice is a messy process, as every practicing lawyer will testify. There are many ways to solve conflicts, and many rule makers (national, international, local, formal, informal, public, private) work on the same problems. Justice sector innova- tors should be able to develop the best approaches in an attractive, competitive environment in which there are a few generally accepted ways to measure potential success of innovations (such as satisfaction of all types of users).10 Fostering competition in the justice sector can be part of a ministerial in- novation policy. This policy would put the minister less in the position of the holder of power who acts, and more in the role of creating a level playing field to make sure that the fairest, most effective, fastest, and lowest-cost solutions survive. For example, take the provision of fair and efficient dispute settlement processes for employment conflicts or coping with the aftermath of large- scale violence. Various civil and criminal public courts might offer different procedures (national, international), industry tribunals, truth and reconcilia- tion commissions (local or national), commissions establishing adequate com- pensation, semibinding mediation services based on existing informal justice mechanisms, or online dispute-resolution platforms.11 10 See Non State Security and Justice in Fragile States, Overseas Development Institute Briefing Paper 73 (Apr. 2012), which also lists some useful rules of engagement in respect to nonstate actors, available at http://www.odi.org.uk/resources/docs/7640.pdf. 11 See, for example, David Pimentel, Rule of Law Reform without Cultural Imperialism? Reinforcing Customary Justice through Collateral Review in Southern Sudan, 2 Hague J. on the Rule of L. 1–28 (2010). http://www.odi.org.uk/resources/docs/7640.pdf The World Bank Legal Review22 In the Netherlands, E-Court promises its clients quick and cheap awards by arbitrators for money claims. Its initiators tell a story of many obstacles based on resistance from bailiffs, state courts, and the ministry of justice, who all saw the existing way of doing things threatened by the concept of E-Court rather than welcoming a new supplier of fair and speedy solutions.12 Yet, this innovation forced the courts to rethink their ways of dealing with similar claims, seeing that the income for the state justice sector from money claims was no longer guaranteed. Did fostering competition enhance the perfor- mance and effectiveness of state courts and private sector dispute resolution? Competition requires a level playing field based on transparency of quality and costs so that clients seeking access to justice can make informed choices and defendants are protected against unfair procedures. In theory, it should be possible, for example, to send all users of a justice process a brief e-mail or text message on their mobile phones asking them to assess a court process they have just gone through based on a number of criteria.13 Their responses could be aggregated and fed into a website for all to see. And based on that, justice clients, justice providers, and ministry officials could see what works best. Justice sector leaders can foster competition by making the performance of justice services more measurable and transparent, by avoiding general monopolies, and by allowing differentiation and specialization. Develop Innovations Once the innovators are at work, the most fruitful ideas must be selected for the actual innovation process. This requires a situation where people with a positive attitude and sufficient resources can nurture the innovative concept. Partnerships between public services providers and private sector organiza- tions can be very fruitful: legal expenses insurance companies can help ensure access to legal aid; online dispute-resolution platforms can be integrated into court procedures. In today’s world, these are no longer rich-country options. Building a prototype early on is recommended, as well as involving end us- ers in the development process. Again, a justice sector leader can take specific actions. Manage Risk Once the developing process starts, a safe environment in which to develop a new concept, allowing for trial and error, is important. In an environment that is not “safe,” where failure is immediately linked to blame and consequences, innovation tends to be difficult. The appetite of the public for trial and er- ror in the justice sector may not be big, however. A minister of justice may be genuinely committed to creating more room for such an approach, but he too is subject to cabinet, parliamentary, and media scrutiny. So creating safe 12 See http://www.innovatingjustice.com/innovations/e-court-the-first-online-private-court. 13 See, for example, the measuring access to justice tool at http://www.innovatingjustice.com /innovations/measuring-the-costs-and-quality-of-access-to-justice. http://www.innovatingjustice.com/innovations/e-court-the-first-online-private-court http://www.innovatingjustice.com/innovations/measuring-the-costs-and-quality-of-access-to-justice http://www.innovatingjustice.com/innovations/measuring-the-costs-and-quality-of-access-to-justice The Justice Innovation Approach 23 spaces for experiments requires risk management. The minister must build it upward within the cabinet, vis-à-vis the prime minister or president and with respect for parliament. The minister of justice must also have a smart media strategy. The minister of justice must project a strong commitment to gradual innovation processes, allowing for trial and error at the ground level, where the innovations need to come from. Quick wins are likely to be important here—specific improvements that show that the innovation climate is produc- ing results, such as savings in the budget, a higher level of satisfaction from victims, more efficient court hearings, less recidivism, or decreasing juvenile delinquency. Reward Innovation Champions People are important. Almost all successful innovations are linked to a key person who devoted years of hard work to making a dream come true. The justice sector is not very good at rewarding such innovation champions. Mak- ing substantial money from innovation is hard, and one of the strengths (and weaknesses) of the justice sector is stressing the professional roles of judges and civil servants rather than personal qualities and strong personalities. A minister of justice is in a unique position to reward people who have worked for many years on improving procedures or systems of rules. Attaching peo- ple’s names to innovations can be done easily; one should never underesti- mate the effect of simple and consistent praise for good achievements.14 Fund Early Development Many innovations in the justice sector—good as they are—trip over two wires: funding for early development and funding for a sustained period of time. The justice sector tends to be funded in a rigid way. The budget and plan- ning cycle is generally quite short. Budgets are structured around fixed de- liverables, which rarely if ever include money for systematic research and development. Courts cannot invest money now that they can recoup in the next years by cost savings or by an increase in court fees for better services or more plaintiffs bringing cases. Justice sector donors may be interested in trying new procedures, but they tend to want specific deliverables: so many judges trained, so many courts and prisons built, a bar association set up. The situation is slightly different in the legal services industry, where research and development budgets from suppliers to law firms have created innovations in specific areas, such as software to help with e-discovery. A minister of justice can make sure that research and development bud- gets exist and that there are ways to recoup initial investments. He can do that within his own ministry, and he can initiate public-private partnerships with 14 An excellent example is the relationship between the International Criminal Court and the partners of the Legal Tools database and Case Matrix Network. The partners carry the costs of their contribution to the network but are also part of the innovation team. Signs of appre- ciation and commitment by the court stimulate the partners in this innovative network. See http://www.legal-tools.org/en/what-are-the-icc-legal-tools/. http://www.legal-tools.org/en/what-are-the-icc-legal-tools/ The World Bank Legal Review24 donors that provide investments in justice innovation with a commitment, for example, that the ministry will take over responsibility for funding the ser- vices once an innovation has been successfully developed. Developing states can lead the way here. Replicate and Scale Up Once an innovation is up and running, its potential for replication and scaling up should be exploited. Models for interactive court hearings developed for civil justice courts can be adapted to administrative law or criminal justice. What has been developed in one court may be useful for similar courts in other countries, but standardizing new practices too early may stifle innova- tion. Change management is necessary as well. Create Incentives A minister of justice can create incentives for justice leaders to try out well- tested innovations that have been developed elsewhere. Allocating extra bud- gets to those who are willing to adopt an innovation is one method. One factor inhibiting justice sector innovation is that each court in each country tends to develop its own working methods, without relying on external suppliers of procedures, supporting software, or protocols for dealing with certain types of crime. A minister of justice can urge justice sector organizations to consider buying tools that are readily available, either those developed by specialized private sector companies or those developed by colleagues in the public sec- tor. If a worldwide market for justice sector technologies were to evolve, the rule of law could be enhanced substantially and many cost savings would be possible. Ministers of justice from developing countries have more choice than ever. Tanzania need not look only at things that worked in Germany, the United Kingdom, or France; it can also look at innovations from, for example, Brazil, India, South Africa, Ethiopia, and Rwanda. Be Aware of Disruptive Innovations Justice sector leaders should be aware of the possibilities of disruptive inno- vations. Online services, such as those offered by Legal Zoom,15 disrupt the market for lawyers and notaries in civil law countries, who are likely to pro- tect their markets by favoring legislation that has been designed without new possibilities in mind, such as the prohibition of legal advice by nonlawyers or the monopolies of notaries public. Because innovations can make basic justice care available to groups that were unable to get any legal assistance in the past, there is every reason to create a level playing field for such new technolo- gies. The paralegal program Timap for Justice has had a disruptive effect on the legal services market in Sierra Leone.16 15 See http://www.legalzoom.com/. 16 See http://www.timapforjustice.org/. http://www.timapforjustice.org/ http://www.legalzoom.com/ The Justice Innovation Approach 25 Consider Long-Term Business Models Assuring longer-term funding for successful justice innovations after the re- search and development phase is often challenging. One of the reasons for this is that consideration of such funding tends to start only once an innovation has been developed. Justice sector leaders should be thinking about the man- agement and budgeting of research and development processes right from the start of any justice innovation initiative.17 Analyze and Learn Innovation cannot exist without critical reflection. Justice sector leaders should ensure that monitoring mechanisms are in place and that new insights can be implemented in improved versions immediately (real-time learning). One reason why the health care sector is so innovative is that benchmarks for new treatments are easy to establish: symptoms disappear and the patient feels better and does not return with the same complaints. Similar metrics for the justice sector would greatly enhance innovation processes, for example, through lower costs, timelier decisions, and higher satisfaction of users (pro- cedural justice, outcome justice). A minister of justice can ensure that a segment of the core budget is re- served for developing such measurement tools and for applying them to the processes and procedures of the system. This is an area par excellence where the minister can enlist civil society organizations, academic networks, and external donors. Civil society organizations can be stimulated to play a role in assessing elements of the justice system and showing where improve- ments are needed. Outcomes measurement could interest donors; and more and more academic institutions are developing rule of law measuring tools.18 What the minister cannot outsource is working with senior civil servants to build a culture in which the challenges that measuring makes visible are har- nessed toward justice innovation. Challenges and Benefits of a Justice Innovation Approach The best way to make the case for a new role for justice sector leaders is to provide an example. Tunisia will go down in history as the spark that set off a forest fire in the Arab world. After President Ben Ali fled, a transitional gov- ernment organized rather effective and open elections, on the basis of which a constitutional assembly worked on a new constitution; as of July 2012, a provisional government was running the country. Ambitions and expecta- tions are high, also relating to the rule of law. There is a general yearning for a better justice system. However, the challenges are tremendous, and there are 17 A very useful tool for this is http://www.businessmodelgeneration.com. 18 For a good overview, see Special Issue on Measuring Rule of Law, 3(2) Hague J. on the Rule of L. (Sep. 2011). http://www.businessmodelgeneration.com The World Bank Legal Review26 no easy answers.19 Stimulating gradual innovation processes around practical problems and showing quick wins may be the most promising way forward. However, justice sectors leaders in Tunisia and other countries in transi- tion face the following challenges. Lack of Trust In Tunisia, a new social contract is being put in place in the midst of a difficult economic and social context. Trust in the state is low.20 For many citizens, state institutions are linked to capricious behavior by people in positions with au- thority. So most people avoid getting in touch with the state institutions; the idea that law protects and can work for people needs to be sold. State institu- tions are not automatically viewed as legitimate. Trust must be regained. The World Development Report 2011 (WDR) con- vincingly argues that legitimate institutions are the best immunizer against internal and external stresses such as the ones Tunisia faces.21 The WDR shows that legitimacy comes with the responsiveness of institutions and that “capac- ity, inclusion, and accountability” are needed.22 In many developing countries, state institutions have limited capacity, are not seen as fully inclusive, and face little accountability. To build legitimate institutions, the WDR argues, justice sector leaders must work from the bottom up, with “good enough coalitions” to create quick and visible wins that show that rule of law is essential. Any minister of justice can build on processes that work in a country. By examining at informal justice systems for medium-level crime, rule-making processes in specific industries, or court procedures giving effective protec- tion against eviction, the minister of justice can stimulate the people involved to innovate and extend these services to the more urgent justice problems the state faces. Coalitions can be built to nurture these processes and to shield them against attempts to corrupt them. Lack of Funds Unemployment, especially in youth, is very high in Tunisia, making invest- ments in labor-intensive industries a priority among the many other economic 19 To name a few: budgets are limited, ideas of justice differ, trust in public officials in the justice sector is limited, and expectations are high. In May 2012, a dispute arose between the government and the association of judges after eighty-one judges were fired for alleged corruption; see http://www.tunisia-live.net/2012/05/31/judges-strike-lifted-following -agreement-with-ministry-of-justice/. 20 See, for example, a survey by the World Justice Project according to which 51 percent of Tunisians believe that the police forces are the most corrupt institution in Tunisian society, available at http://www.tunisia-live.net/2012/05/29/according-to-poll-80-of-tunisians -feel-free-to-express-themselves/. See also remarks by the head of the national anticorrup- tion agency during a HiiL seminar held in Tunis (Apr. 2011), on record with the authors. 21 World Development Report 2011: Conflict, Security and Development 74 et seq. (World Bank 2011). 22 Id., at 84. http://www.tunisia-live.net/2012/05/31/judges-strike-lifted-following-agreement-with-ministry-of-justice/ http://www.tunisia-live.net/2012/05/29/according-to-poll-80-of-tunisians-feel-free-to-express-themselves/ http://www.tunisia-live.net/2012/05/31/judges-strike-lifted-following-agreement-with-ministry-of-justice/ http://www.tunisia-live.net/2012/05/29/according-to-poll-80-of-tunisians-feel-free-to-express-themselves/ The Justice Innovation Approach 27 challenges. In 2009, the Tunisian GDP stood at around US$40 billion, or US$8 per person.23 This is three to five times less than the GDP in Euro Area coun- tries, making it inconceivable that Tunisia will be able to invest heavily in court infrastructure and expensive professionals to deliver justice sector ser- vices. But Tunisian citizens do not want less “justice” than European ones, nor should they be asked to accept less. So a country like Tunisia has every inter- est in stimulating innovation in the justice sector so that it can deliver better justice for its money. Innovative ways to deliver justice at low cost can be found throughout the world; a transitioning country such as Tunisia presents a window of op- portunity to adopt and adapt these innovations to a local setting. Can court processes be organized in such a way that more solutions are delivered per judge? In Nicaragua, the Facilitadores Judiciales program equipped a judge with a team of facilitadores, who live in villages far away from the courthouse. They mediate under the judge’s supervision and assist with bringing the cases that do not settle to court. Sierra Leone and South Africa pioneered the use of paralegals at a fraction of the cost of training judges and lawyers. In large- scale litigation, which will also occur in Tunisia, expert evidence is often key. Increasing the reliability of the fact-finding process and decreasing the costs of dealing with expertise were the goal of a procedure for a dialogue between experts at a court hearing developed in Australia.24 Online dispute resolution now resolves 60 million disputes between buyers and sellers on eBay, holding promise for dealing with large numbers of disputes anywhere in the world.25 Power Relations Influence on justice sector institutions is always part of a broader struggle for power, especially in situations of transition. Military versus civilian power brokers. Landowners versus landless. Employers versus employees. Domi- nant ethnic groups versus groups that feel oppressed. Secular versus religious norms. Rule of law gets politicized quickly. The stimulation of justice innovation can be a road to reform without po- litical turmoil. It is less about big principles (which is not to say they do not count) and more about little steps that deal with specific problems. Gradual but deliberate improvement of employment complaint procedures can be organized from the bottom up: targets can include more voice for parties at hearings, speedier resolution, more settlement, lower costs, clearer criteria for remedies, and clearer reasons in judgments. This approach is likely to be more effective than a heated discussion about the independence of courts or whether employees should have protection against dismissal. Innovation in- cludes developing transparent monitoring mechanisms that show the extent 23 The Economist, World in Figures, 2012, at The Economist website. 24 See http://www.innovatingjustice.com/innovations/concurrent-expert-evidence. 25 See http://pages.ebay.com/coverage/index.html. http://pages.ebay.com/coverage/index.html http://www.innovatingjustice.com/innovations/concurrent-expert-evidence The World Bank Legal Review28 to which the clients of the courts experienced a neutral procedure with equal opportunities for both parties. Indonesia has found interesting ways to cope with the sharia versus secu- lar dilemma. The area of family relationships is perhaps the foremost area where sharia law has impact (corporal punishment in criminal law is seldom applied in practice in most countries that have sharia law). Facing a choice between formal courts and religious courts, Indonesian couples wanting a di- vorce overwhelmingly choose religious ones. Religious courts are more open to innovation, working in close cooperation with Australian courts to improve their services. Transitional Justice Tunisia is a place where the concept of transition permeates. The judicial or- ganization needs fundamental reorganizing: some judges too closely linked to the former regime may have to go, a role for council for the judiciary must be found, performance mechanisms to hold judges accountable and effective ways to distribute budgets must be developed, and the question of special- ization versus generalization is on the table, as is the question of how it can support courts. Law making represents a huge challenge. The country is em- barking on a fundamental redesign, facing the task of ensuring the quality and coherence of laws. Both the judges and the clients of the justice system need better access to legal information. Key elements of the “hard” justice infra- structure—courthouses and published and available laws—are in bad shape. For a minister of justice, these issues are fraught with choices for which it will be difficult to build support within the courts and the institutions involved in law making. A strategy based on creating a level playing field for justice innovation assumes that justice sector innovators take initiatives to start improving ser- vices. And those improved services should be the point of departure, not the organization itself: ways to create needs for higher quality, more trustworthy services, and lower-cost delivery. For example, if a group of judges decides that disputes over land is an urgent priority and they propose terms of refer- ence for a new procedure, such as transparency of criteria for allocating land and compensation, the more organizational problems of specialization and court independence may be solved on the way. The goal is for the government to be less the structure that is supposed to solve a problem and more a place where leaders work to empower those closest to the problem to creatively resolve concrete, close-to-the-ground issues. Conclusion Justice sector leaders can improve the rule of law by incorporating the justice innovation approach. Because this approach enlists the whole of society (jus- tice users and providers), benefits from best practices and technologies devel- oped in other countries, and harnesses the knowledge of those working on The Justice Innovation Approach 29 problems already, it can deliver more value and justice with less money than other approaches. However, organizing the necessary space for justice innova- tion is not easy in any context, and is even more challenging in the context of a developing state. Good justice sector leadership is a key component of the effort. Legal sys- tems have their own dynamics and tend to move slowly. The WDR estimates that it takes 17 to 41 years to establish basic trust in the rule of law.26 The at- titude of expecting central, top-down coordination is very strong in the justice sector, and many very good ideas now wait until a new constitution is en- acted, the law of procedure is changed, or a budget is cleared. However, there are many opportunities for a justice sector leader to create and manage justice innovation in the meantime. There is certainly risk involved in doing so, but the potential benefits are huge. 26 World Development Report, supra note 21, at 11. 31 Legal Empowerment of the Poor: Past, Present, Future Hassane Cissé The concept that law plays a significant role in promoting economic devel- opment is well established. The nature of that significance, in the context of development narratives, traditionally has been rooted in law’s connection to strong institutions and good governance: the presence of law can be consid- ered a prerequisite for effective government. Effective government has come to be treated as an essential ingredient in the development recipe, and law or, more specifically, the “rule of law,” is the condition for that ingredient. In an effort to reimagine how law can fit into development strategies, scholars and practitioners have widened the traditional focus on institutions and government machinery to bring the people themselves into view: the poor have become a subject in law and development discourse, rather than simply the indirect, long-term beneficiaries of institutional reform. Many scholars and practitioners now argue that law can be used as a tool in the hands of the poor, a tool that they can use to improve their own lives. This process has become known as legal empowerment. This chapter maps the emergence and progress of the legal empowerment movement, if it can be called that. This field is still young, and disagreements over its direction are unresolved. Basic questions of priorities and strategies remain contested; assumptions must be tested further; more data need to be collected. Nevertheless, the movement has much promise and is gaining ac- ceptance. It should be taken seriously by everyone concerned with using the law to end poverty. The Emergence of Legal Empowerment and Its Place in the Rule of Law Agenda Legal empowerment of the poor (LEP) is a relatively new frontier in thinking about how the law can affect the lives of the poor and what can and should be done to empower the poor to use the law for their betterment. By evoking law and power together, LEP directly challenges traditional ideas about the role of law in the lives of the poor. At the same time, the LEP paradigm is not a complete rejection of other ways of theorizing about the purpose of rule of law in development. LEP both reaffirms and reacts against the older develop- ment agenda of advancing the rule of law, and remains closely connected to The author thanks Matthew Moorhead for his invaluable assistance in the preparation of this article. Stephen Golub and Sam Muller also provided constructive comments. Responsibility for errors or omissions remains with the author. The World Bank Legal Review32 it. To understand the origins and evolution of LEP, and possibly its future, one must also understand the nature of this connection with traditional rule of law approaches. The importance of the rule of law in human development is generally acknowledged, despite enduring disagreements about the degree of that im- portance. Lawyers, economists, and development specialists must continue to explore new ways in which the law can alleviate poverty. As practitioners endeavor to improve the imperfect understanding of the role of law in human welfare, advances continue to be made in rule of law scholarship.1 As new insights are uncovered, many traditional ways of thinking about how law can lift people out of poverty become ripe for reevaluation. As the scholarship grows and this process of reevaluation unfolds, elements of what might be termed the “classical rule of law approach” receive more critical attention. In particular, an excessive focus on institutions and state structures, a supposed hallmark of the classic rule of law approach, has been criticized for overlook- ing the needs of the poor. A growing awareness of this risk has caused scholars and development practitioners to conceive of a new way of thinking about how the law can contribute to development: LEP. A central claim of the LEP approach is that poverty endures because, in part, people are forced to live their lives without legal protection. The focus on legal empowerment is intended to strengthen existing and ongoing efforts to further the rule of law agenda. It is also, to some extent, a reprimand of those efforts. Legal empowerment as a strategy for development has gained prominence, in part, on the back of criticism of, or frustration with, the outcomes of the more established rule of law agenda. That agenda can mean many things to different people, and some sense of its meaning is set out here. “Rule of law” is a concept with a broad scope that was established as a development objective and method decades before LEP emerged. Generally, the rule of law is defined in one of two ways. The first emphasizes elements of substantive justice; the second emphasizes the procedural aspects of a system in which the rule of law prevails.2 The conditions of both definitions must be met if the rule of law can be said to exist in any given system. A functional rule of law system that provides both procedural effectiveness and substan- tive justice is obviously important to human welfare and the satisfaction of justice claims. What is less clear is exactly how much the rule of law matters, and how effective rule of law interventions have been in improving develop- ment outcomes for the poor. 1 See, for example, Thomas Carothers ed., Promoting the Rule of Law Abroad: In Search of Knowl- edge (Carnegie Endowment for International Peace 2006); James J. Heckman, Robert L. Nelson, & Lee Cabatingan ed., Global Perspectives on the Rule of Law (Routledge 2010); and Michael J. Trebilcock & Ronald J. Daniels ed., Rule of Law Reform and Development: Charting the Fragile Path of Progress (Edward Elgar 2008). 2 Paul P. Craig, Formal and Substantive Conceptions of the Rule of Law: An Analytical Framework, 467 Public Law (1997). Legal Empowerment of the Poor: Past, Present, Future 33 The impact of improvements in the rule of law environment on develop- ment outcomes is notoriously hard to quantify. A number of attempts have been made. Daniel Kaufmann and his colleagues measured several aspects of governance, including the rule of law, over time and across more than two hundred countries.3 They suggest that a nation’s GDP increases noticeably by moving ahead when improvements are made in an index of rule of law indicators. Despite efforts such as these, however, it may never be possible to measure the impact of the rule of law in neat percentages. Kaufmann’s study acknowledges that the difficulties inherent in proving a link between the rule of law and economic growth may preclude such measurement. Nevertheless, the study supports a general consensus that there is a positive correlation be- tween economic development and strong legal systems. The way in which the rule of law has evolved en route to becoming part of mainstream development orthodoxy is perhaps best exemplified by the ap- proach of the World Bank, one of the world’s foremost development institu- tions, to the issue. When the Bank realized that the rule of law and judicial reform were related to economic development, the Bank became involved in LEP efforts. The connection to economic development is a critical factor that enables the Bank to engage in legal reform, because its Articles of Agreement prohibit it from taking into account anything other than “economic consid- erations” in its lending operations.4 Before the Bank could be comfortable in- volving itself in LEP work, it needed to accept that the quality of governance affects economic development. This was a delicate task for an institution that is prohibited from “interfering in the political affairs” of its members, yet as evidence of the importance of governance and the rule of law in economic per- formance grew, the Bank responded. In 1990, the general counsel of the Bank issued a legal opinion concluding that the Bank “may favorably respond to a country’s request for assistance in the field of legal reform, if it finds it relevant to the country’s economic development and to the success of the Bank’s lend- ing strategy for the country.”5 Although hard to quantify, the correlation between rule of law indicators and economic development is real. Beyond this assumption, what matters to people is identifying precisely what kind of rule of law initiatives serve them best. As the field matures and the evidence of what works and what does not starts to mount, the “second generation” of rule of law scholarship is challeng- ing many assumptions about how to conduct legal reform and what to expect from the results. In the past decade, some scholars and commentators have 3 Daniel Kaufmann, Aart Kraay, & Massimo Mastruzzi, Governance Matters VI: Governance In- dicators for 1996–2006, World Bank Policy Research Working Paper No. 4280 (2007). See also, for example, Juan Carlos Botero, Robert L. Nelson, & Christine Pratt, Indices and Indicators of Justice, Governance and the Rule of Law: An Overview, 3 Hague J. on the Rule of L. 153 (2011). 4 International Bank for Reconstruction and Development, article IV, section 10. 5 Ibrahim Shihata, Issues of “Governance” in the Borrowing Members—The Extent of Their Rel- evance under the Bank’s Articles of Agreement 25 (Dec. 21, 1990). The World Bank Legal Review34 come to question the dominant ways of thinking about the rule of law. LEP has emerged from this persistent questioning. As Stephen Golub posits, LEP is partly an alternative to the perceived fail- ings of rule of law orthodoxy.6 Golub classifies many of the law-reform efforts of the major international development actors as top-down efforts that pay insufficient attention to the actual needs of the poor. According to Golub, rule of law orthodoxy has been said to focus “too much on law, lawyers, and state institutions, and too little on development, the poor, and civil society.”7 LEP is intended to address these particular deficiencies. In the words of critics such as Thomas Carothers, typical efforts to promote the rule of law cannot convincingly demonstrate “how the rule of law develops in societies and how such development can be stimulated beyond simplistic efforts to copy institutional forms.”8 LEP, however, is more focused on the real needs of the poor. As a development strategy, it has been said to both advance and transcend the rule of law. LEP advances the rule of law in the sense that em- powered people will be in a position to demand good governance, and it tran- scends the rule of law by lifting the focus from governance to more general poverty alleviation.9 A number of definitions of LEP are used in the literature. The UN Com- mission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor (CLEP) defines LEP as “a pro- cess of systemic change through which the poor and excluded become able to use the law, the legal system, and legal services to protect and advance their rights and interests as citizens and economic actors.”10 Golub expands on the basic definition of LEP by differentiating it from rule of law orthodoxy on four issues. First, LEP requires lawyers to view the poor as partners instead of simply providing advice. Second, the poor should aspire to influence public policy directly in order to avoid falling into a top-down approach. Third, LEP should employ nonjudicial strategies alongside strictly legal ones. Fourth, law should be integrated into a broader range of development-related activities.11 These features enable LEP to serve as a “useful organizing framework to navi- gate through the complex landscape which has resulted from the fusion of 6 The term “rule of law orthodoxy” is used by Frank Upham in Mythmaking in the Rule of Law Orthodoxy, Carnegie Endowment Working Paper No. 30, Rule of Law Series, Democracy and Rule of Law Project (Carnegie Endowment for International Peace 2002). 7 Stephen Golub, Beyond Rule of Law Orthodoxy: The Legal Empowerment Alternative, Carnegie Endowment Working Paper No. 41, Rule of Law Series, Democracy and Rule of Law Project 3 (Carnegie Endowment for International Peace 2003). 8 Thomas Carothers, Promoting the Rule of Law Abroad: The Problem of Knowledge, Carnegie Endowment Working Paper No. 34, Rule of Law Series, Democracy and Rule of Law Project 3 (Carnegie Endowment for International Peace 2003). 9 Golub, supra note 7, at 7. 10 Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor, Making the Law Work for Everyone: Volume One, Report of the Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor 3 (2008). 11 Golub, supra note 7, at 4. Legal Empowerment of the Poor: Past, Present, Future 35 the two tectonic plates driving development today: governance and poverty reduction.”12 Cementing the Place of Legal Empowerment: The Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor Scholars such as Banik13 and Golub have been working in the area of LEP for years, but the idea that LEP can be a force for development gained international recognition when it became the subject of a landmark UN commission in 2008. The CLEP report brought international attention and credibility to LEP and provides a road map for mainstreaming LEP into development work.14 The report does not understate the view of the commissioners that legal empower- ment is of the utmost importance. Central to the report is the bold claim that “four billion people around the world are robbed of the chance to better their lives and climb out of poverty, because they are excluded from the rule of law.”15 Influential names lend their authority to this statement. The commis- sion was cochaired by former US secretary of state Madeline Albright and re- nowned Peruvian economist Hernando de Soto, and comprised 23 members, of whom 19 were current or former presidents, prime ministers, senior jurists, or other government officials of the highest rank. For the commissioners, poverty partly stems from “legal exclusion,” or exclusion from the protections of the rule of law. The report concluded that “by expanding and deepening legal protection, poor people will be better able to free themselves from poverty.”16 Four areas, or “pillars,” are critical to the task of extending legal protection to the 4 billion excluded people, accord- ing to the CLEP report. The first pillar, access to justice and the rule of law, is essential to the others. Legal empowerment is impossible if poor people do not have access to a functional judicial system of some kind. Efforts in this regard include a range of measures to make judicial systems more accessible to the poor and oriented to their needs. The three other pillars are legal rights: property rights, labor rights, and so-called business rights. The CLEP report emphasizes the foundation of LEP in international human rights law, particu- larly in Article 1 of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, but it does not elaborate on the nature of this connection to human rights discourse.17 The CLEP report is a welcome contribution to the broader international development agenda. It moves from the traditional focus on strengthening laws and institutions to a focus on the needs of the poor. The prestige and 12 Ana Palacio, Legal Empowerment of the Poor: An Action Agenda for the World Bank 14 (2006). 13 Dan Banik ed., Rights and Legal Empowerment in Eradicating Poverty (Ashgate 2008). 14 Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor, supra note 10. 15 Id., at 1. 16 Gordon Brown, Foreword to Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor, supra note 10. 17 Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor, supra note 10, at 29. The World Bank Legal Review36 scale of the commission have permanently elevated the status of LEP as a development strategy and have similarly increased the general awareness of its purpose and benefits. The response to the CLEP report has included a UN General Assembly resolution endorsing the findings, as well as discussions about possible funding initiatives among key donors. Rather than assuming that the poor will automatically benefit by increas- ing the resources available to courts, the report argues that poverty is best addressed by moving resources and power directly into the hands of the poor. It provides a map to redirect the poverty-fighting rule of law agenda toward a more constructive path. Nonetheless, the report has been the subject of criticism. Golub, for ex- ample, criticizes it for unquestioningly adopting certain neoliberal economic assumptions, for attaching excessive importance to the role of legal exclusion in perpetuating poverty, for taking insufficient notice of preexisting research on LEP, for proposing a top-down approach to what is claimed to be a bottom- up development strategy, and for assuming that rational persuasion will suf- fice to convince elites to surrender political power to the poor.18 The CLEP report arguably overreaches in claiming that 4 billion people are impoverished as a result of their exclusion from the protection of the law. Many scholars, such as Banik, have noted that this claim is not properly sub- stantiated.19 In addition to legal exclusion, many important factors interact in complex and opaque ways to produce poverty, including cultural exclusion, economic failure, high population growth, and political instability. To over- emphasize the poverty-fighting effect of LEP is to risk undermining the entire LEP project. If the CLEP report risks overreaching in its 4-billion-people claim, the focus on four pillars is equally limiting. Property, labor, and business rights are not the only areas in which empowerment can make a difference in poor people’s lives. The poor must be empowered to gain access to education, to benefit from criminal justice, and to combat violence against women, for example.20 Certain policy prescriptions proposed by the CLEP report are vulnerable to the charge that they are unworkable in practice and do not acknowledge the entrenched political obstacles that stand in the way of LEP.21 The CLEP report says that political leadership is necessary for change and assumes that elites can be persuaded by rational arguments to empower the poor. In the words of 18 Stephen Golub, The Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor: One Big Step Forward and a Few Steps Back for Development Policy and Practice, 1 Hague J. on the Rule of L. 101, 105 (2009). 19 Dan Banik, Legal Empowerment as a Conceptual and Operational Tool in Poverty Eradication, 1 Hague J. on the Rule of L. 117, 118 (2009). 20 Banik, supra note 19, at 125. 21 Sam Muller & Maurits Barendrecht consider how justice sector leadership can overcome these obstacles in their chapter in this volume. Legal Empowerment of the Poor: Past, Present, Future 37 CLEP, LEP “does not require its political champions to be saints (although that could be useful) but only to recognize an enlightened self-interest . . . what better political legacy than to have made a lasting contribution to the develop- ment of one’s country.”22 The unavoidable truth is that power is a relative concept. When one per- son is empowered, the power that another person has over him or her is di- minished. In the relationships between people, power is both won and lost. In other words, the process of empowering people creates winners and losers. It is not realistic to assume that elites, when confronted by rational economic arguments, will surrender their relative advantage over the poor to further a greater good. Shifting power to the poor is a difficult and highly political task that requires a political strategy to accompany economic theorizing. A technocratic approach that fails to directly address local political exigencies will not succeed. In many developing countries, networks of elites connecting the government and private sector will staunchly resist LEP because LEP pre- sents a direct challenge to the existing power structure. As Matthew Stephens notes, the CLEP report does not adequately address this formidable challenge. The report contains “no strategy for political change, little evidence produced to justify the suggested reforms and an absence of implementable responses to turn theory into practice. These deficiencies diminish [the CLEP report’s] value to practitioners and will curtail its policy impact.”23 No commission, no matter how distinguished or experienced its member- ship, can reveal a magic recipe to make political obstacles to good develop- ment policy disappear. It would be unfair and unrealistic to demand such a recipe from CLEP. However, CLEP does not offer much guidance on this issue beyond stating that “politics cannot be wished away. Powerful actors must be co-opted, won over.”24 Many entrenched elites will not be amenable to co- option under any circumstances and will never be partners in LEP. If elites are uncooperative, the only approach that remains is a bottom-up strategy that empowers the poor and the disenfranchised to protect their own interests. This is, fundamentally, what LEP is about: empowering the poor to improve their own situation. Contemporary Issues in Legal Empowerment of the Poor As the responses to the CLEP report make clear, there are limits to what LEP can achieve and substantial barriers in the way of success. Although law has a significant role to play in defeating poverty, the poor themselves often see the law as a barrier to prosperity and security, rather than as a tool for overcoming 22 Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor, supra note 10, at 45–46. 23 Matthew Stephens, The Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor: An Opportunity Missed, 1 Hague J. on the Rule of L. 132, 147 (2009). 24 Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor, supra note 10, at 43. The World Bank Legal Review38 poverty.25 LEP is about transforming the way the poor experience the law, shifting from a constraining to an empowering experience. Efforts to move in this direction can be grouped by themes, or perhaps by challenges. This sec- tion explores a few of the more prominent issues faced by the LEP movement. Access to Justice The CLEP report’s focus on access to justice is appropriate. LEP has significant potential as a development strategy, particularly through the promotion of ac- cess to justice for the poor. Making justice available to the poor can unlock the greatest development benefits of LEP. Accessing justice means seeing wrongs righted and having the confidence that remedies are available to correct such wrongs that may occur. These are important outcomes to people everywhere. Confidence in the capacity to access justice gives the poor the green light to in- vest in their own future and that of their families, secure in the knowledge that their entitlements will be protected. More formally, “access to justice” means “the ability of people to seek and obtain a remedy through formal or informal institutions of justice, and in conformity with human rights standards.”26 This definition acknowledges that access to justice is about more than sim- ply the formal, or official, justice system of courts and judges. Informal justice systems, often in the form of precolonial conflict resolution systems, have an essential role to play. Poor people in developing countries tend to seek justice from informal systems rather than from the formal court system.27 There is a long list of well-known obstacles between the poor and a just outcome in the formal justice system: procedural deficiencies, prohibitive costs, mistrust of the law, fear of the authorities, corruption, language barriers, excessive delays in decision making, and perceived institutional illegitimacy.28 These are just a few examples of the many reasons that formal justice systems are usually out of reach of the poor and why the poor turn to informal systems. Of course, formal systems are extremely important and must be strengthened. Informal justice systems alone are not a long-term solution to the problem of provid- ing justice to the general population. Informal justice systems can perpetu- ate discrimination against women or be problematic from other human rights perspectives. Nevertheless, allowing for these limitations, the role of informal systems in delivering justice to poor people must be acknowledged and sup- ported as part of any comprehensive LEP strategy. It must be noted that access to justice has been a concern of legal prac- titioners and legal policymakers for centuries and was a central objective of legal reform long before the emergence of LEP. The World Bank, for example, targeted access to justice in several of its earliest legal reform projects. Ac- 25 Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor, supra note 10, at 3. 26 UNDP, Access to Justice Is the Ability of People to Seek and Obtain a Remedy through Formal or Informal Institutions of Justice, and in Conformity with Human Rights Standards (2005). 27 Banik, supra note 13, at 14. 28 Banik, supra note 13, at 15. Legal Empowerment of the Poor: Past, Present, Future 39 cess to justice first appeared as a World Bank objective in 1996 in the Ecuador Judicial Reform Project.29 Since then, access to justice has been an objective in legal reform projects in countries such as Armenia, Bangladesh, El Salvador, Guatemala, Honduras, Kazakhstan, Mexico, Mongolia, Morocco, Peru, and the Philippines.30 Thus, although much that LEP offers is new, its concern with access to justice is not. What the proponents of LEP promise, however, is that LEP, with its focus on empowering those most in need of improved access to justice, can provide better ways of doing just that. A recent World Bank project in Sierra Leone is an example of a project designed to empower the poor to access justice. The World Bank’s Justice for the Poor program worked with Namati, an organization devoted to legal em- powerment, to train community-based paralegals to overcome obstacles in the delivery of health services.31 Inadequate or nonexistent health care is one of the gravest disadvantages endured by Sierra Leone’s poor. The delivery of health care services is impeded by corruption, mismanagement, and a lack of resources. The failure to provide health care on such a scale is a grave injustice, and the paralegal program is an attempt to use the law to empower Sierra Leoneans to demand justice from health care providers. Health care is a good candidate for a LEP strategy because the delivery of health services encompasses much more than medical staff and medicines. To be effective, the delivery of any public service must be accountable. Much of Sierra Leone’s underperformance in health care can be attributed to the failures of the state institutions that are nominally responsible for health care delivery. The paralegal program grew from the view that addressing these failures requires an understanding of the policy and regulations governing health care, which in turn means an understanding of what the state is sup- posed to provide and to whom, and where pressure should be applied when the state fails to deliver. Sierra Leone does not have enough lawyers for this task. In many of Si- erra Leone’s districts, community paralegals—that is, nonlawyers with some training in law and government administration—help citizens navigate gov- ernment services. Until now, however, paralegals have not been used to im- prove accountability in the delivery of health services. The Justice for the Poor program assesses whether paralegals help improve service outcomes by, for example, making regular, unannounced visits to the health clinic to help en- sure that maternal and child health services are truly provided free of charge. Ultimately, the goal is for paralegals to help empower their communities. A general increase in the level of “social accountability” in Sierra Leonean villages will help people access the services to which they are entitled. Once 29 Roberto Laver, The World Bank and Judicial Reform: Overcoming “Blind Spots” in the Approach to Judicial Independence, 22 Duke J. Comp. & Intl. L. 183, 196 (2012). 30 Id. 31 Justice for the Poor. The World Bank Legal Review40 taught how to pursue redress in the health system, people will gain experi- ence and confidence in engaging with state institutions and will learn how to hold them accountable. Gender Inequality In practice, empowering the poor largely means empowering women. The World Development Report 2012: Gender Equality and Development examines and details the many ways poor women are disempowered.32 Despite prog- ress in recent decades, the likelihood of women dying in childbirth in Sub- Saharan Africa and parts of South Asia remains comparable to that in Northern Europe in the nineteenth century.33 In many countries, women enjoy fewer legal protections and property rights than do men. Women are far more likely than men to work in low-paying, low-status “pink collar” occupations, to face life-threatening violence in the home, and to be unrepresented in senior lev- els of politics and management.34 In its extent, severity, and ubiquity, gender inequality is perhaps the most pressing area calling for LEP strategies. As the World Development Report concludes, gender inequality matters for two reasons: First, gender equality matters intrinsically, because the ability to live the life of one’s own choosing and be spared from absolute privation is a basic human right and should be equal for everyone, indepen- dent of whether one is male or female. Second, gender equality mat- ters instrumentally, because greater gender equality contributes to economic efficiency and the achievement of other key development outcomes.35 An example of the way in which targeting women can empower large num- bers of the poor and how grassroots legal empowerment can instigate change at a national level is a project conducted by the World Bank and its partners in Indonesia. The Bank’s Justice for the Poor program, together with the Aus- tralian Agency for International Development (AusAID), the Family Court of Australia, and PEKKA (an Indonesian civil society organization supporting women-headed households), developed a number of innovative programs to empower women to use their legal identity to exercise their rights and access benefits. A few statistics demonstrate the importance to poor people of establishing legal identity in Indonesia. According to the Indonesian Bureau of Statistics, women head almost 10 million Indonesian households.36 In order to access 32 World Bank, World Development Report 2012: Gender Equality and Development (World Bank 2011). 33 Id., at 2. 34 Id. 35 Id., at 3. 36 Indonesian Bureau of Statistics (Badan Pusat Statistik), Statistik Gender 2009 18 (Bureau of Statistics 2010). Legal Empowerment of the Poor: Past, Present, Future 41 government services such as health insurance, rice subsidies, and cash trans- fer payments, female heads of household must prove to local government au- thorities that they are, in fact, the head of the household. To obtain an identity card giving her head-of-household status, a woman must prove that, if she has been married or divorced, her marriage or divorce was legally registered. This presents a serious obstacle for many women. Research by PEKKA shows that more than 50 percent of the marriages and 86 percent of the divorces of its members are not legally registered because they were not brought before a court.37 In Indonesia, the relevant court is usually a religious court. The reli- gious courts handle 98 percent of divorce cases, which themselves account for 50 percent of all court cases in Indonesia.38 To access poverty alleviation programs, health services, and education programs for herself and her family, a woman must have a legal identity and a status as the head of her household. Legal marriage and divorce also matter to her children. Unregistered or illegal marriages and divorces, and the resulting lack of birth certificates for the children of such unions, feed an intergenera- tional cycle of poverty and social exclusion. When women are disempowered, their children and other family members often join them in poverty. The Women’s Legal Empowerment (WLE) program was designed to help women in West Java formalize their legal identity by building on PEKKA’s existing empowerment programs. The WLE program had both demand- and supply-side empowerment objectives. On the demand side, the program aimed to inform communities of their rights and encourage them to insist that those rights be respected; on the supply side, it aimed to improve the capacity of the government administration and legal system to recognize and protect the rights of poor women. The WLE program used various tools to work to- ward these objectives. In the villages, trained paralegals disseminated legal information about family law and domestic violence, provided assistance to local women, and supported grassroots advocacy efforts. A forum, compris- ing judges, public prosecutors, police, local government officials, NGO repre- sentatives, and academics, was established at the district level to conduct legal awareness and outreach activities. Women used the services of the paralegals and the forum members to obtain hundreds of birth certificates for their chil- dren and to organize circuit courts to visit villages to formalize marriages and divorces. The outcome was the empowerment to a transformative degree of the in- dividual women concerned. On a larger scale, the research and results gener- ated by the WLE and its associated projects contributed to policy develop- ments across Indonesia. After becoming aware of the problems of accessing justice in the religious courts, the government increased the religious courts’ 37 Justice for the Poor, Increasing Access to Justice for Women, the Poor, and Those Living in Remote Areas: An Indonesian Case Study, Briefing Note 6, No. 2 (Mar. 2011). 38 Id. Data taken from Supreme Court annual report for 2009. The World Bank Legal Review42 budget 18-fold in two years.39 New laws have been passed requiring Indone- sian courts to provide legal aid services to the poor, an encouraging example of the impact that LEP can have on policy making by elites. Property Rights LEP is a work in progress. Even as the concept has gained currency as a de- velopment strategy in government and international institutions, the contours and nuances of what LEP means in practice, or what a good LEP policy looks like, remain unresolved. To a frustrated observer, LEP may appear to suffer “from a lack of clarity at many levels of definition, operation, and evaluation.”40 The connection between theory and public policy has not been clearly iden- tified, despite the work of CLEP. Much research remains to be done about what policies and interventions are the most effective at empowering the poor. In the meantime, certain theories about the best kind of LEP policies remain hotly debated. The most important, and possibly the most contested, issue in the brief history of LEP concerns the protection of property rights. Hernando de Soto, the cochair of the CLEP report, has long argued that de- veloping countries are constrained by the dominance of informal economies.41 According to this view, without an effective legal system that recognizes and enforces property rights, a country cannot develop a functioning market and consequently cannot produce or allocate capital. If poor people in developing countries are to escape poverty, their property rights must be formalized and protected so that they can exploit the capital value of that property. This view forms a central pillar of the CLEP report, which urges develop- ing countries to extend property rights to more people by accommodating access to housing, protecting the supply of credit, enacting land reform, and standardizing and uniformly applying property law in the court system. This focus on the importance of formal property rights is influential, and variations of it are widely shared,42 but it has been criticized by some schol- ars. Alan Gilbert has said that de Soto is guilty of “fanning the delusion that anyone, anywhere, can become a fully fledged capitalist,” whereas in fact focusing on securing property rights tends to “persuade policy makers that they need do little more than offer title deeds and then leave the market to do everything else.”43 Others have argued that a Western-inspired vision of indi- vidual property rights is ill suited to economies that have long operated under a system of collective or community ownership of land. 39 Justice for the Poor, supra note 37. 40 Palacio, supra note 12, at 6. 41 Hernando de Soto, The Mystery of Capital: Why Capitalism Triumphs in the West and Fails Every- where Else (Random House 2000). 42 See, for example, Robert D. Cooter & Hans-Bernd Schäfer, Solomon’s Knot: How Law Can End the Poverty of Nations (Princeton U. Press 2012). 43 Alan Gilbert, On the Mystery of Capital and the Myths of Hernando de Soto: What Difference Does Legal Title Make? International Development Planning Review 15 (Liverpool U. Press 2002). Legal Empowerment of the Poor: Past, Present, Future 43 Development policy makers have learned through bitter experience that a uniform, one-size-fits-all approach to policy interventions in poor countries can have unfortunate, and sometimes disastrous, consequences. The same principle certainly applies to legal reform and to property law reform. If a legal reform is to take hold and be effective, it must be perceived as legitimate, not as an alien custom imposed by external forces. Property law reform will have a better chance of taking root if it strengthens rights that individuals already believe they possess or should possess. The reforms must support ex- isting aspirations, not completely reorder society. That is, reforms to systems of property law must incorporate local understandings of the relationship be- tween people and the land they inhabit. This is particularly important where a collective or spiritual attachment to land prevails: land is not always con- ceptualized as “property,” something that can be bought and sold.44 If policy makers bear these sensitivities in mind, much can be done to empower the poor in the area of property rights. Networks LEP is not solely, or perhaps even primarily, a “legal” strategy to reduce pov- erty. As Golub notes, “legal empowerment is about power more than about law.”45 An aim of LEP is to avoid the fixation on formal legal institutions (and lawyers) that some say is a mark of the traditional rule of law agenda and to focus on more community-based methods. Supporting strong and effective judicial institutions is an important part of strengthening the rule of law in a country, but without complementary efforts to empower poor people to use the law, this cannot be considered a LEP strategy. LEP activities can be catego- rized in a number of different ways. Golub’s list is a good example: investing in civil society, engaging NGOs at a country-specific level, integrating with socioeconomic development projects, taking a long-term approach, support- ing impact-oriented research, incentivizing government personnel to support legal empowerment, and making LEP a policy priority for donor countries as well as for developing countries.46 The emergence of organizations that are dedicated to these community- based activities is an indication of the status of LEP within the broader de- velopment agenda. Consider Namati, with which, as noted above, the World Bank is working on a project in Sierra Leone. Namati describes itself as an organization that is focused on “innovations in legal empowerment” and that supports grassroots programs that move away from the familiar model that involves many lawyers.47 Typically, according to Namati, a legal empower- ment program will contain a small group of lawyers and a larger front-line 44 For an interesting discussion of this issue, see Edward Robbins, Formalisation of Land and Housing Tenure to Empower the Poor: Simple Nostrum or Complex Challenge? in Rights and Legal Empowerment in Eradicating Poverty 175 (Dan Banik ed., Ashgate 2008). 45 Golub, supra note 18, at 108. 46 Golub, supra note 18, at 113–16. 47 See http://www.namati.org. http://www.namati.org The World Bank Legal Review44 group of community paralegals. Paralegals work closely with communities, deploy a flexible range of tools, and connect to lawyers for high-level advo- cacy if their front-line efforts prove to be insufficient or inappropriate. In ad- dition to these community-level programs, Namati believes that LEP requires reforms to state institutions to encourage the participation and ownership of individuals and communities. Examples of such institutional reforms include simplifying land registration procedures, strengthening grievance mecha- nisms to respond to failures in public service delivery, and improving access to government information. As more organizations and development agencies adopt LEP approaches, evidence of a global LEP discourse is emerging. The Global Legal Empower- ment Network is an interesting example. The network, the result of a collabo- ration between the World Bank and the Open Society Justice Initiative and hosted by Namati, provides a forum for those involved in LEP, including de- velopment agencies, community paralegals, concerned citizens, NGOs, pub- lic interest lawyers, journalists, and government officials, to share knowledge and experience. The network aims to connect practitioners to each other and to build a strong foundation and momentum for LEP. As of this writing, the net- work consists of an online database for exchanging practical resources, such as a paralegal training manual. Practitioners are invited to form subgroups based on geographical regions or themes and to participate in face-to-face regional meetings. The future of the LEP movement lies in networks that connect develop- ment practitioners with the poor, development practitioners with develop- ment practitioners, and the poor with the poor. If poor people are to realize the benefits of empowerment, such connections must be made. Solidarity and the strengthening of community ties are essential if the power of the poor is to be expressed; that is, if it is to be any kind of power worth having. Conclusion LEP is a new movement in a much older tradition, and it shares with that tra- dition a commitment to bring the law to bear on development challenges. By focusing on those who are directly affected by a lack of economic opportunity and by prioritizing their needs, LEP has the potential to make the development agenda work better for the poor. That is, after all, the purpose of development efforts. Prominently inscribed in the foyer of the World Bank headquarters in Washington, DC, are the words “Our dream is a world free of poverty.” LEP can contribute to turning that dream into a reality, but substantial challenges exist. The priorities for LEP should be to launch pilot projects based on solid LEP principles, to examine the results of those projects for insights, and, above all, to collect more data: data about what the poor want, what the poor think the law can do for them, and how the poor want to empower themselves. As the data grow and the principles and basic strategies of LEP are refined, LEP will assume an important place in the antipoverty agenda. 45 Beyond the Orthodoxy of Rule of Law and Justice Sector Reform A Framework for Legal Empowerment and Innovation through the Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities Janet e. Lord, deepti Samant raJa, and peter BLanck The Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities (CRPD),1 the first legally binding international human rights treaty to address the rights and fundamental freedoms of one billion persons, provides a framework for legal empowerment and innovation that challenges traditional conceptualizations of justice-oriented development intervention. The CRPD implicitly renounces the orthodox view that top-down justice sector and rule of law initiatives should be the primary target of law and development efforts. Although the CRPD does not discount—in fact, it explicitly requires—the reform of legal systems, justice sectors, and institutions in meeting its obligations, it goes well beyond the traditional focus on development donors to embrace an empower- ment model that implicates nonformal and decentralized justice and admin- istrative systems and processes, local communities in development, and the duties of private as well as public actors in fostering inclusion. The legal em- powerment framework set forth in the CRPD has significant implications not only for bridging rights and development in the context of disability but also more broadly for other marginalized groups living in poverty. The UN General Assembly adopted the CRPD, along with its Optional Protocol,2 by general consensus and the instruments were opened for signature by states parties on March 30, 2007.3 It attained the requisite 20 This research was funded in part by grants to Blanck from the U.S. Department of Educa- tion, the National Institute on Disability and Rehabilitation Research (NIDRR), and Syracuse University; for details see http://bbi.syr.edu. This chapter is adapted from presentations made at the session “Persons with Disabilities: Innovation and Empowerment through the Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities,” World Bank Law, Justice and Devel- opment Week, Washington, D.C., 2011. The authors wish to thank participants in the panel session for their inputs. The authors wish to acknowledge and thank Jesse Feitel, Max Smith, and Josh Tumen for assisting with background research for this chapter. 1 Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities, GA Res. 61/106, UN Doc. A/ RES/61/106 (Dec. 13, 2006) (hereinafter, CRPD). 2 Optional Protocol to the Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities, GA Res. 61/106, Annex II, UN Doc. A/RES/61/106 ( Jan. 24, 2007) (hereinafter, Optional Protocol). 3 Updated information on signatures and ratifications is available at http://www.un.org /esa/socdev/enable/rights/humanrights.htm (accessed Jul. 25, 2012). http://bbi.syr.edu http://www.un.org/esa/socdev/enable/rights/humanrights.htm http://www.un.org/esa/socdev/enable/rights/humanrights.htm The World Bank Legal Review46 ratifications in short order, triggering its entry into force on May 3, 2008.4 The impetus for drafting the treaty was the exclusion of an estimated 1 billion persons with disabilities from their communities, where they are routinely de- nied access to education, employment, health care services, and basic needs.5 More often than not, persons with disabilities live in poverty and experience lower levels of education and income compared to the general population.6 Research indicates that in all countries, disability prevalence rates are signifi- cantly higher among groups with lower economic status, underscoring the reinforcing relationship between poverty and disability.7 Prior to the adoption of the CRPD, no international instrument compre- hensively addressed the multitude of barriers experienced by persons with disabilities, and only a handful of states had well-developed disability rights law and policy frameworks.8 Where states did have disability-related leg- islation, often such laws explicitly introduced disability discrimination, for example, denying persons with disabilities the right to vote, to obtain an education, to serve as a juror, to open a bank account, to own property, or to work in certain sectors. In other instances, provisions relating to disability evoked welfare-oriented as opposed to comprehensive human rights protec- tion. Although the human rights of persons with disabilities were implicitly addressed within the framework of general human rights law, and were to some extent reflected in several disability-specific nonbinding initiatives, this framework was insufficient to advance disability human rights and provide an impetus for change at the state level.9 4 For more on the rights of persons with disabilities generally, see Human Rights and Persons with Disabilities, www.un.org/esa/socdev/enable/rights/humanrights.htm (ac- cessed Jul. 24, 2012). For a comprehensive overview of the CRPD, see Rosemary Kayess & Phillip French, Out of Darkness into Light? Introducing the Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities, 8(1) Human Rights L. Rev. 1–34 (2008); M. A. Stein & J. E. Lord, Future Pros- pects for the United Nations Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities, in The UN Convention on the Rights of Person with Disabilities: European and Scandinavian Perspectives (O. M. Arnardóttir & G. Quinn ed., Martinus Nijhoff 2008). 5 See World Health Organization and World Bank, World Report on Disability 29 (2011), available at http://www.who.int/disabilities/world_report/2011/report/en/ (accessed Jul. 25, 2012). 6 Id., at 39. 7 Daniel Mont, Measuring Disability Prevalence, SP Discussion Paper No. 0706 (Disability & Development Team, HDNSP, World Bank, Mar. 2007), available at http://siteresources .worldbank.org/DISABILITY/Resources/Data/MontPrevalence.pdf. See also Sophie Mitra, Aleksandra Posarac, Brandon Vick, Disability and Poverty in Developing Countries: A Multidi- mensional Study World Development (Jul. 27, 2012). 8 See Gerard Quinn, Resisting the “Temptation of Elegance”: Can the Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities Socialise States in Rights Behaviour? in The UN Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities: European and Scandinavian Perspectives 215, 224–29 (1st ed., O. M. Arnardóttir & G. Quinn ed., Martinus Nijhoff 2009). 9 For a review of the need for further development of domestic disability law frameworks, see Theresia Degener & Gerard Quinn, A Survey of International, Comparative and Regional Disability Law Reform, Disability Rights Law and Policy: International and National Perspectives 3, 25-45 (Mary Lou Breslin & Sylvia Yee ed., Disability Rights Education and Defense Fund 2002), available at http://www.dredf.org/international/degener_quinn.html (accessed Jul. 24, 2012). www.un.org/esa/socdev/enable/rights/humanrights.htm http://www.who.int/disabilities/world_report/2011/report/en/ http://siteresources.worldbank.org/DISABILITY/Resources/Data/MontPrevalence.pdf http://siteresources.worldbank.org/DISABILITY/Resources/Data/MontPrevalence.pdf http://www.dredf.org/international/degener_quinn.html Beyond the Orthodoxy of Rule of Law and Justice Sector Reform 47 The CRPD fills this gap insofar as it provides a road map for the develop- ment and reform of domestic disability law and policy in alignment with in- ternational human rights principles, but also in its creation of mechanisms and duties to foster the empowerment of disability advocates and their representa- tive organizations. In obligating states parties to pursue specific national-level implementation measures to give full effect to its provisions, the CRPD ad- vances the kind of broad-based approach to human rights advocacy contem- plated in the legal empowerment literature.10 Moreover, recognition of the link between poverty and disability in the CRPD provides added support for legal empowerment approaches in the context of disability.11 In sum, the CRPD calls for innovation to advance domestic disability advocacy to support the human rights and fundamental freedoms of the globe’s “largest minority.”12 CRPD: Structure and Overall Content The CRPD comprises 25 preambular paragraphs and 50 operative articles that set out the historical progression of international disability rights and high- light issues of particular import.13 It has an introductory set of provisions out- lining its purpose (Article 1), key definitions (Article 2), and several general (cross-cutting) articles that are to be interpreted and applied across all articles of the treaty text (Articles 3–9).14 The CRPD is the first international human rights treaty to prohibit discrimination on the basis of disability and, signifi- cantly, to require the provision of reasonable accommodation in order to meet its nondiscrimination and equality requirement. It has a novel provision (Ar- ticle 9, Accessibility) detailing state obligations in the area of accessibility that is broadly defined and is driving innovation in numerous spheres and affects not only states but private actors as well. The CRPD enumerates specific sub- stantive civil, political, economic, social, and cultural rights (Articles 10–30). It establishes a system of monitoring and implementation (Articles 31–40), and it includes provisions that govern the operation of the CRPD (Articles 41–50). The general requirements set forth in Article 4 make clear the need to ground CRPD obligations in national law, policy, and programming in con- sultation with persons with disabilities. Thus, Article 4 requires states parties to consult with and involve persons with disabilities in developing and im- plementing legislation and policies and in decision-making processes, includ- ing development planning. In this sense, the CRPD underscores the need to engage with stakeholders and their representative organizations, reflecting a 10 See Stephen Golub & Kim McQuay, Legal Empowerment: Advancing Good Governance and Pov- erty Reduction, in Law and Policy Reform at the Asian Development Bank (ADB 2001); Anna Pala- cio, Legal Empowerment of the Poor: An Action Agenda for the World Bank (ARD 2006). 11 World Report on Disability, supra note 5, at 39. 12 Id., at 29. 13 CRPD, supra note 1. 14 The CRPD articles are available at http://www.un.org/disabilities/default.asp?id=259 (ac- cessed Jul. 25, 2012). http://www.un.org/disabilities/default.asp?id=259 The World Bank Legal Review48 shift toward legal empowerment approaches, as opposed to only stand-alone, top-down rule of law interventions. Top-down initiatives are needed and are required by the CRPD—including training of lawyers and judiciaries—but these interventions rest within the context of a legal empowerment, access to justice approach. The CRPD lays out a framework for national-level monitoring that in- cludes cross-governmental coordination, independent monitoring (inferred to be performed by a national human rights institution, or NHRI), and stake- holder participation (Article 33). A Committee on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities—the CRPD’s treaty-monitoring body—is tasked with monitor- ing implementation by states parties through its oversight of the mandatory reporting requirement and the issuance of general recommendations for the state party concerned.15 The Optional Protocol to the CRPD,16 consisting of 18 articles, gives the committee competence to examine individual complaints with regard to alleged CRPD violations by parties to the protocol. It allows states parties to opt into participation in individual and group communica- tions procedures, as well as an inquiry procedure, all of which are overseen by the committee.17 These mechanisms are important vehicles for empowering local disabled people’s organizations (DPOs) to bring individual violations and systemic abuses to the attention of the committee for its review. An innovative mechanism that can facilitate disability advocacy is the es- tablishment of a periodic meeting of a Conference of States Parties (COSP), as set forth under Article 40 of the CRPD. Disability advocates and their rep- resentative organizations are using the COSP in ways that reflect creative ap- proaches to legal empowerment.18 The CRPD stands out among the core human rights conventions in affirm- ing the role and impact of international cooperation in promoting the imple- mentation of progressive disability reforms and in establishing a framework to foster international cooperation and inclusive development programming. Through Article 32, the CRPD is the first human rights convention to detail the kinds of measures states parties can take to facilitate the implementation of the convention.19 Article 32 promotes the need to ensure that international 15 For an overview of the development, mandate, and future potential of the CRPD committee, see M. A. Stein & J. E. Lord, Monitoring the Committee on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities: Innovations, Lost Opportunities, and Future Potential, 31 Hum. Rights Q. 689 (2010). 16 Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities, Optional Protocol, United Nations, available at http://www.un.org/disabilities/default.asp?id=311 (accessed Jul. 25, 2012). 17 The committee undertook consideration of an individual communication in which it found a violation of CRPD rights. See Committee on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities, HM v. Sweden, Communication No. 3/2011, Views adopted by the committee at its seventh session (Apr. 16–27, 2012), available at http://www.ohchr.org/EN/HRBodies/CRPD/Pages/Juris prudence.aspx. 18 See UN Enable, Conference of States Parties, available at http://www.un.org/disabilities /default.asp?id=1535 (accessed Jul. 25, 2012). 19 Katherine Guernsey, Marco Nicoli, & Alberto Ninio, Convention on the Rights of Persons with http://www.un.org/disabilities/default.asp?id=311 http://www.ohchr.org/EN/HRBodies/CRPD/Pages/Jurisprudence.aspx http://www.un.org/disabilities/default.asp?id=1535 http://www.ohchr.org/EN/HRBodies/CRPD/Pages/Jurisprudence.aspx http://www.un.org/disabilities/default.asp?id=1535 Beyond the Orthodoxy of Rule of Law and Justice Sector Reform 49 cooperation initiatives, including development programs, are accessible and inclusive of people with disabilities.20 Thus, it gives credence to the impor- tance of mainstreaming disability in development to achieve not only the goals and objectives of this convention but also goals for poverty reduction and empowerment within the development community as a whole.21 States are encouraged to support capacity building and the exchange of knowledge and best practices, strengthen research collaborations and access to scientific knowledge, and offer technical and economic assistance to help meet a state’s obligations under the convention.22 This provision may extend CRPD stan- dards, via development programming, to effect change in discrete contexts such as electoral law reform and practice, community-based rehabilitation, and DPO capacity building. The convention sets forth general obligations familiar to human rights treaties—prompting national law reform and domestic incorporation of its provisions. It provides a framework for national-level disability rights advo- cacy and action. Significantly, the convention draws together a diverse set of obligations that, when surveyed, constitute a map of advocacy and empower- ment opportunities at the local, national, and international level. In so doing, the CRPD plots a course for a human rights practice that goes beyond tradi- tional justice sector and rule of law interventions and includes legal empow- erment and innovation that is locally driven, community focused, and civil society oriented.23 The CRPD as a Framework for Empowerment and Innovation: Beyond Rule of Law and Justice Sector Orthodoxy The CRPD evokes a model of disability rights realization reflective of the lit- erature on legal empowerment. This is specifically reflected in the following articles: • Articles 4 and 8 specify that raising disability rights awareness is a gen- eral obligation requiring strategies aimed at dismantling barriers posed by stigma and discrimination, making the justice system more accessible. • Article 4 proposes that law is a tool for strengthening legal rights through disability legal reform and legal framework development in terms of both substance and process. Disabilities: Its Implementation and Relevance for the World Bank, SP Discussion Paper No. 0712 (World Bank 2007). 20 CRPD, supra note 1. 21 UN Enable, The Millennium Development Goals (MDGs) and Disability, available at http:// www.un.org/disabilities/default.asp?id=1470 (accessed Jul. 25, 2012). 22 CRPD, supra note 1. 23 For a discussion of the limitations of orthodox justice sector and rule of law interventions, see Golub & McQuay, supra note 10. http://www.un.org/disabilities/default.asp?id=1470 http://www.un.org/disabilities/default.asp?id=1470 The World Bank Legal Review50 • Articles 13, 28, and 32 facilitate disability rights implementation through strategies of inclusion, including in justice sector institutional capacity building. • Articles 16, 33, and 34–40 provide strategies for strengthening the moni- toring and enforcement of disability rights. Although countries have enthusiastically supported, ratified, and signed the CRPD,24 many face challenges in implementing the convention due to disempowering social contexts for persons with disabilities and underdevel- oped legal systems. This reality raises a variety of issues, among them the differentiation between developed and developing countries in capacities for implementation and the varied perspectives on the nature and definition of disability. The CRPD does not provide a concrete definition of disability but states that “persons with disabilities include those who have long-term physical, mental, intellectual or sensory impairments which in interaction with various barriers may hinder their full and effective participation in society on an equal basis with others.”25 This conceptualization demands a shift in how policy- makers think about disability. For example, disability laws in some countries define disability with a finite list of observable impairments, ignoring hidden disabilities that arise from chronic or mental illness, learning and cognitive difficulty, and accident, and disregarding environmental and interactional is- sues completely.26 Prior to the adoption of the CRPD, many disability laws and policies op- erated mainly from the perspective of medical and welfare perspectives on disability, in which a person with a disability is presumed to be incapable of equal participation in society.27 This conception leads to a dependence on wel- fare policies and charity programs to address the “needs” of persons with dis- abilities and their families.28 Many of the concepts set forth in the CRPD may seem foreign to policymakers and at times may be at odds with the legislative approaches used in some countries. Thus, states parties need to bring about significant law and policy reform and development to align with the shift re- quired by the CRPD29—presenting challenges, but also creating opportunities for significant innovation. 24 For an updated list of ratifications and signatories, see http://www.un.org/disabilities /countries.asp?id=166 (accessed Jul. 25, 2012). 25 CRDP, Article 1, supra note 1. 26 See, for example, the case of India in Andrew Byrnes, Disability Discrimination Law and the Asian and Pacific Region (Paper 3), in Resources on Harmonization of National Legislation with the Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities in Asia and the Pacific, available at http:// www.unescap.org/sdd/issues/disability/crpd/files/Paper-III-Andrew-20110121.pdf. 27 Kayess & French, supra note 4. 28 Id. 29 Arlene Kanter, The Promise and Challenge of the United Nations Convention on the Rights of Per- sons with Disabilities, 34 Syracuse J. Intl. L. & Com. 287 (2007). http://www.un.org/disabilities/countries.asp?id=166 http://www.unescap.org/sdd/issues/disability/crpd/files/Paper-III-Andrew-20110121.pdf http://www.un.org/disabilities/countries.asp?id=166 http://www.unescap.org/sdd/issues/disability/crpd/files/Paper-III-Andrew-20110121.pdf Beyond the Orthodoxy of Rule of Law and Justice Sector Reform 51 The provisions and motivations under Article 32, which covers interna- tional cooperation, offer the potential to assist states parties struggling with challenges in crafting required innovations and facilitating access to resources to aid in implementation. Promoting the exchange of technical knowledge and best practices while providing resources for capacity building will aid government workers and practitioners at all levels to usher in improvements and reforms to policies, programs, and practices. Addressing disability in international aid and development funding and support will help low- and middle-income states parties to provide far-reaching and inclusive programs that meet their goals and obligations under the CRPD. The following sections discuss the general schema of legal empowerment and innovation set forth in the CRPD and provide illustrations of how CRPD obligations are pursued in different ways to effect change. These include rais- ing awareness of disability rights; strengthening disability rights; facilitating disability rights; and improving monitoring and enforcement of disability rights. Raising Awareness of Disability Rights The various barriers faced by persons with disabilities in developing countries combine to restrict their access to information and awareness of their rights, a situation also faced by persons living in poverty and other disadvantaged groups. As emphasized in the World Report on Disability, persons with disabili- ties are likely to live in poverty and are very often restricted in their access to education, employment, transportation, and health care and often live in iso- lation from the wider community.30 The social determinants of legal empower- ment, therefore, are severely restricted for persons with disabilities. The need for awareness-building initiatives, including legal literacy programs, partici- patory human rights education tied to action at the local level, legal aid bu- reaus, and inclusive development programming aiming to integrate persons with disabilities into mainstream programming (such as health, economic de- velopment, democracy and governance, and education), are important and implicit in the CRPD framework. The CRPD recognizes in Article 8 (awareness raising) that a precondition to legal empowerment is combating the stigma that seeds discrimination. In so doing, the CRPD signals the central role that legal empowerment plays in ad- dressing the situation of persons with disabilities (and indeed any historically marginalized group). Consistent with legal empowerment models, awareness raising is a fundamental precondition of disability rights realization and com- prises both understanding of legal rights and an appreciation of how to claim those rights through action.31 CRPD provisions that require public consulta- tion as well as accessibility measures in the contexts of law and policy making, 30 World Report on Disability, supra note 5, at 39. 31 Golub & McQuay, supra note 10, at 7. The World Bank Legal Review52 training health professionals in disability rights awareness, and the general obligation to promote the training of professionals and staff working with per- sons with disabilities in the CRPD rights framework are important facilitators of rights awareness and are central to legal empowerment.32 There are numerous examples of innovative disability rights awareness- raising initiatives, many of which are integrated into development program- ming, as opposed to implementation limited to one-off training events. In Li- beria, during the historic 2004 elections in which the first woman African head of state was elected, DPOs used the electoral process to raise the voice and visibility of Liberians with disabilities. At the time, Liberian DPOs were aware of the CRPD drafting process and requested, as part of their election work, information about international standards on disability to help them draft a national disability law. Facilitated through the international election adminis- tration organization, the International Foundation for Electoral Systems and BlueLaw International LLP, the project’s goal was to foster DPO cooperation through the creation of a coalition that affected all phases of the electoral pro- cess—voter education and registration, polling, electoral observation and monitoring, and postelection assessment.33 The methodology was to position members of the Liberian disability community as leaders and experts and to conduct participatory human rights education in raising awareness and understanding about election access on the part of election commissioners.34 A poignant illustration of successful ad- vocacy occurred during a training of 50 election officials from the Liberian National Election Commission. During the workshop, disability advocates, including persons with various types of disabilities, simulated vote casting at a polling station to illustrate the numerous barriers that they had experi- enced in previous elections.35 This method used humor that was effective, and it imparted serious messages of discrimination and exclusion based on stereo- typing and generalized lack of knowledge. Drawing on their individual ex- periences, members of the group demonstrated the barriers that can stand in the way of access and participation for a voter with disabilities, ranging from physical and communication barriers experienced by persons with physical and sensory disabilities to barriers rooted in ignorance and stigma. 32 CRPD, supra note 1, at Article 4. 33 Janet E. Lord & Michael A. Stein, Participation in International Agreements as Transformative Social Change: The UN Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities, in Making Rights Real ( Jody Heymann ed., Cambridge U. Press 2012). 34 Id. 35 For more on using participatory human rights education to forward disability rights, see Janet E. Lord and Nancy Flowers, Human Rights Education and Grassroots Peace Building, in Human Rights and Conflict: New Actors, Strategies and Ethical Dilemmas ( Julie A. Mertus & Jeff Helsing ed., United States Institute of Peace 2006). Beyond the Orthodoxy of Rule of Law and Justice Sector Reform 53 Strengthening Disability Rights To strengthen disability law frameworks so they are more in line with inter- national standards on disability rights, the substance as well as the process of the law must be reformed. Substantive and procedural reforms can cre- ate accessible and consumer-oriented dispute-settlement procedures. These range from legal claims brought before courts and human rights tribunals to electoral complaints mechanisms to complaints procedures of national human rights institutions. Procedural reforms are a core part of enhancing access to justice for marginalized groups, including enhancing the accessibility of no- tice requirements, the right to be heard, access to information rights, and the provision of reasonable accommodations. Legislative Reform to Modify Legal Frameworks and Stimulate Legal Empowerment Although legislation and policies by themselves do not assure full implemen- tation of the CRPD, they are a necessary pillar of the effort to facilitate change. Similar to states parties to other core human rights conventions, states parties to the CRPD are required to adopt specific legislation that prohibits discrimi- nation in all spheres.36 Such laws should aim at eliminating barriers to access that constitute both formal and substantive discrimination, attribute obliga- tions to public and private actors, and introduce measures to bring about equitable access to all rights. Although the CRPD is relatively new, it has already promoted significant law and policy shifts. This work is being under- taken at various levels, including in constitutional development and reform, national-level law reform and development, and targeted law reforms in dis- crete contexts. For some countries, antidiscrimination legislation will require a change in the overall approach toward tackling inequities. For example, Japan does not have comprehensive antidiscrimination laws and policies, and the concept of nondiscrimination in regard to disability is not considered a part of the broader civil and human rights initiative.37 With its ratification of the CRPD, Japan is developing disability discrimination law and policy for the first time.38 States parties should consider using incentives to encourage public and pri- vate actors to change their attitudes and behavior in relation to individuals and groups facing systemic discrimination, or penalize them in case of noncom- pliance. The identification and elimination of barriers will frequently require devoting greater resources to issues of access. Particular attention must be given to ensuring that laws and policies are implemented in practice. In Nepal, DPOs worked to ensure that the voices of persons with disabili- ties were heard during the drafting of a new constitution. The Kathmandu 36 CRPD, supra note 1, at Article 4. 37 J. Nakagawa & P. Blanck, Future of Disability Law in Japan: Employment and Accommodation, 33(1) Loy. L.A. Intl. & Comp. L. Rev. 173 (2010). 38 Id. The World Bank Legal Review54 Center for Independent Living in Nepal held workshops that were strategi- cally designed by the organizers to build linkages among DPOs, civil society organizations, and international actors—such as the United Nations—in the constitution-drafting process. Although few DPOs in the country had pre- viously focused on law and policy advocacy, one objective of the constitu- tion-drafting participation was to help build the capacity of DPOs to engage actively in law and policy reform and development and to engage with in- ternational civil society partners to increase understanding of international standards on disability.39 In other countries, notably South Africa, Uganda, Zambia, and Thailand,40 DPOs have likewise used constitution-building processes to leverage disabil- ity rights. Ecuador issued a presidential executive decree in 2007 to promote the development of disability programs across all sectors and introduced a chapter on disability in its 2008 constitution.41 Article 54 of Kenya’s 2010 con- stitution “seeks to minimize barriers to equalization of opportunities in all as- pects of social-cultural, economic and political life” for persons with disabili- ties.42 In Egypt, efforts are under way to adopt a national disability law, situate disability within the new constitutional framework, and revise the election law in conformity with the CRPD. Enhancing political participation is critical in postconflict and transitioning countries. Legal Empowerment to Support the Reform of Policies, Plans, and Strategies Since the adoption of the CRPD, countries have started developing disability action plans where none existed previously, as well as incorporating disabil- ity into their broader national action plans. Thailand developed the National Plan for Persons with Disabilities’ Quality of Life Development Plan 2007–11 to issue guidelines for an integrated approach to disability and development programs in the country.43 States parties should ensure that strategies, policies, and plans of action are in place and implemented in order to address barri- ers to access. Economic policies, such as budgetary allocations and measures to stimulate economic growth, should take into account the need to guaran- tee the effective enjoyment of all CRPD rights. Public and private institutions should be required to develop plans of action to address nondiscrimination, 39 Lord & Stein, supra note 33. 40 The Thai constitution of 2007 includes “anti-discrimination provisions and guarantees acces- sibility to social welfare and services for persons with disabilities.” For legislative develop- ments as reported to the CRPD committee, see United Nations, Compilation of Legislative Mea- sures Undertaken in the Implementation of the Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities: 2011 Update (CRPD/CSP/2011/CRP.5), available at http://www.un.org/disabilities/docu ments/COP/crpd_csp_2011_crp.5.doc (accessed May 24, 2012). 41 Id. 42 Id. 43 Id. For a more extensive discussion of law and policy within the context of HIV and disabil- ity, see Janet E. Lord, HIV/AIDS, Disability and Discrimination: A Thematic Guide on Inclusive Law, Policy and Programming (One Billion Strong, Washington, D.C. 2012). http://www.un.org/disabilities/documents/COP/crpd_csp_2011_crp.5.doc http://www.un.org/disabilities/documents/COP/crpd_csp_2011_crp.5.doc Beyond the Orthodoxy of Rule of Law and Justice Sector Reform 55 and states should conduct human rights education and training programs for public officials and make such training available to judges and candidates for judicial appointments. Projects aimed at building human rights knowledge and advocacy tech- niques are often pursued in a vacuum, effectively disconnected from follow- up action plans. For instance, some efforts to train local DPOs regarding the CRPD have been provided without enabling those groups to exercise their newly acquired capabilities. Consequently, although DPOs have gained knowledge, they remain unsure how to appropriately utilize it. The Harvard Law School Project on Disability, in cooperation with BlueLaw International and American Institutes for Research, worked with a coalition of DPOs in Zambia. The objectives were to learn more about the CRPD with a specific aim to make public health services, including HIV/AIDS education, be disability inclusive.44 One of the strategies was the placement of a disability advocate on the team implementing a large-scale HIV program involving a large interna- tional organization and a number of local organizations. The provision of dis- ability expertise in the form of a dedicated staff member and the provision of training to a network of disability advocates engaged in both disability policy and HIV education at the community level increased the capacity of DPOs and enabled them to achieve better access to health care, the CRPD goal they identified as a priority. Facilitating Disability Rights Measures in the CRPD aim to ensure the facilitation of the rights set forth in the treaty. The CRPD is a framework in which disability rights may be ex- ercised through a variety of measures that identify and then dismantle the barriers that stand in the way of the legal empowerment of persons with dis- abilities. Such facilitation efforts include the accessibility measures identified in Article 9, the measures of reasonable accommodation and positive mea- sures in Article 5, institutional and individual capacity building, and means to facilitate access to the mechanisms of justice. Accessibility in Virtual Spaces The CRPD has helped to bridge another major frontier in disability em- powerment and inclusion in the mainstream—ensuring that accessibility is not limited to the physical realm alone but extends to virtual spaces as well. Information and communication technologies (ICTs) are a major driver in social and professional interchange in today’s world and permeate almost all transactions and interactions in society. Today, ICT-enabled services and resources are central features of many socioeconomic development initia- tives, including promoting access to banking, health care, education, income 44 For a brief discussion of this project, see http://www.bluelawinternational.com (accessed Jul. 24, 2012). http://www.bluelawinternational.com The World Bank Legal Review56 generation, disaster response and management, and social networking and civic participation.45 This raises the stakes in ensuring that ICTs are accessible to people with disabilities for two reasons: one, ICT-enabled development can significantly help to level the playing field for people with disabilities;46 and two, the lack of accessibility will add to their exclusion from major develop- ment programs, leading to further marginalization.47 The CRPD addresses accessible ICTs and assistive technologies (AT) throughout, most specifically in Articles 9, 21, and 26, emphasizing the criti- cal role these technologies play in realizing all rights, such as access to justice, freedom of expression, and rights to political participation, education, health rehabilitation, and employment.48 However, Web accessibility and the avail- ability of accessible ICTs remain low despite the wide ratification of the CRPD. The Global Initiative for Inclusive ICTs (G3ict) issued the CRPD Progress Re- port on ICT Accessibility 2010 based on a survey of 33 countries. This report found that • Only 58 percent of the countries studied included ICT in accessibility defi- nitions in laws or regulations. • Only 36 percent had laws, policies, or programs to define public procure- ment rules for accessible ICTs. • Sixty one percent enabled persons with disabilities to input information in accessible and usable formats to access services offered online. • Sixty seven percent had laws, policies, or programs that ensure that gov- ernment communications using ICTs are provided in accessible and alter- native formats (for example, sign language or Braille). The pervasiveness of ICTs in most socioeconomic domains requires states parties to develop laws and policies to support a comprehensive, coordi- nated, and successful approach to promoting ICT accessibility for all. Peter Blanck and colleagues at the Burton Blatt Institute at Syracuse University have worked closely with the European Union (EU) to assess the adequacy of laws and policies to ensure broad ICT accessibility. The lessons learned through this work resonate across countries. 45 Deepti Samant, Rebecca Matter, & Mark Harniss, Realizing the Potential of Accessible ICTs in Developing Countries, in Disability & Rehabilitation: Assistive Technology (Informa Healthcare 2012, doi:10.3109/17483107.2012.669022, available at http://informahealthcare.com/doi /pdfplus/10.3109/17483107.2012.669022) also forthcoming in print. 46 Id. 47 Peter Blanck, Towards a Right under the ADA to Web Access for People with Cognitive Dis- abilities (Coleman Institute for Cognitive Disabilities 2012), available at http://www.cole maninstitute.org/images/documents/research_development/2012CTowardsARightUnder TheADA.pdf; M. V. Vicente & A. J. Lopez, A Multidimensional Analysis of the Disability Digital Divide: Some Evidence for Internet Use, 26(1) The Information Society 48 –64 (2010). 48 CRPD (2006), available at http://www.un.org/disabilities/default.asp?navid=13&pid=150 (accessed Jul. 24, 2012). http://informahealthcare.com/doi/pdfplus/10.3109/17483107.2012.669022 http://www.colemaninstitute.org/images/documents/research_development/2012CTowardsARightUnderTheADA.pdf http://www.un.org/disabilities/default.asp?navid=13&pid=150 http://www.colemaninstitute.org/images/documents/research_development/2012CTowardsARightUnderTheADA.pdf http://www.colemaninstitute.org/images/documents/research_development/2012CTowardsARightUnderTheADA.pdf http://informahealthcare.com/doi/pdfplus/10.3109/17483107.2012.669022 Beyond the Orthodoxy of Rule of Law and Justice Sector Reform 57 Laws, policies, and regulations must address accessibility in the entire accessibility supply chain, including “content production, content transmis- sion, and content rendering.”49 Thus, policies must cover the producers and developers as well as the deployers of technology (that is, service providers such as banks).50 Different countries have different approaches for such an undertaking. For example, in the United States different pieces of legislation covering different products, agencies, and sectors that utilize ICT-based ser- vices—a piecemeal approach—coexist with broad-sweeping legislation such as the Americans with Disabilities Act.51 Depending on the political climate and national interest, both approaches may need to be used. Additionally, states parties should promote collaboration and agreement among the differ- ent stakeholders such as consumers, service providers, manufacturers, and law enforcement to create broad support for institutional drive due to the dif- fering interests of and impacts on each stakeholder group.52 Issues such as ICT accessibility encompass the need for top-down (impose direct obligations on the supply side) as well as bottom-up (rights for users/consumers) types of legislation.53 Some states will need to support public and private mechanisms for harmonization toward uniformity of law. Another issue that is increasingly a challenge for law and policymakers is that of convergence—the “erosion of boundaries” between different types of previously separate ICT products and services such as the transmission of television content delivered over the Internet.54 The expansion of such services may fall in the gray areas not clearly covered by accessibility legislation or regulation. As discussed by Cullen et al.: Telephony over the Internet often falls outside the scope of legisla- tion dealing with accessibility of voice telephony and there is a lack of clarity as to whether interactive TV is a broadcast or a telecommu- nications service, or neither of these but a new class of service from an e-Accessibility regulatory point of view.55 Finally, it is important to address the issue of the existence and trans- ferability of standards and regulations for ICT products and services across 49 Kevin Cullen et al., Accessibility of ICT Products and Services to Disabled and Older People: To- wards a Framework for Further Development of EU Legislation or Other Co-ordination Measures on eAccessibility (European Commission 2008). 50 Id. 51 William N. Myhill, Law & Policy Challenges for Achieving an Accessible eSociety: Lessons from the United States, in European Yearbook on Disability Law vol. 2 (L. Waddington & G. Quinn ed., Intersentia 2010). 52 Samant, Matter, & Harniss supra note 45. 53 Cullen et al., supra note 49. 54 Rajendra Singh & Siddhartha Raja, Convergence in Information and Communication Technol- ogy: Strategic and Regulatory Considerations (World Bank 2010), available at http://publi cations.worldbank.org/index.php?main_page=product_info&cPath=0&products_id=23785 (accessed Jul. 25, 2012). 55 Cullen et al., supra note 49, at 65. http://publications.worldbank.org/index.php?main_page=product_info&cPath=0&products_id=23785 http://publications.worldbank.org/index.php?main_page=product_info&cPath=0&products_id=23785 The World Bank Legal Review58 national boundaries. The lack of accessibility standards and policies across regions can create significant challenges for individuals with disabilities in an increasingly global society and impede progress toward the fulfillment of the CRPD. The challenge of CRPD implementation in the context of virtual spaces raises numerous issues pertaining to developing-country needs and underdeveloped capacity. Common but Differentiated Obligations between Developed and Developing States? The notion that international obligations may introduce flexibility and differ- ential treatment for rich and poor countries is a pragmatic response to real disparities in technical and economic capacities to comply fully with treaty standards. Bodansky’s typology of treaty design features that affect obliga- tory stringency in the international environmental realm is instructive in this regard; it includes flexible or contextual commitments; differential standards; and reservations.56 Although it may be anathema to suggest that human rights obligations are somehow contingent or differential on the basis of resources, there are indeed concepts that do, in essence, render obligations either less stringent in the sense of temporality (that is, progressive realization in rela- tion to economic, social, and cultural rights)57 or more flexible in the sense of providing states with a margin of appreciation for the operationalization of a requirement to suit country contexts or in allowing reservations, declarations, and understandings.58 Thus, it is possible to speak in terms of “common but differentiated re- sponsibilities” in the CRPD.59 However, legal, institutional, and economic un- derdevelopment is not an escape hatch for avoiding compliance. The CRPD goes further than any other human rights convention in establishing a frame- work for international cooperation that accommodates divergent levels of economic development and unequal capacities to address disability rights in a comprehensive manner.60 Article 32 represents one model for making interna- tional human rights law responsive to such challenges and to foster substan- tive disability rights equality among states.61 56 D. Bodansky, The Art and Craft of International Environmental Law (President and Fellows of Harvard College 2010). 57 CRPD, supra note 1, at Article 4(2). 58 Id., at Article 46. 59 C. Stone, Common but Differentiated Responsibilities in International Law, 98 Am. J. Intl. L. 276– 301 (2004). 60 Philippe Cullet, Differential Treatment in International Law: Towards a New Paradigm of Inter- state Relations, 10 European J. Intl. L. 549–82 (1999). For a helpful discussion of implementa- tion challenges in another context, see G. Shaffer, The Challenges of WTO Law: Strategies for Developing Country Adaptation, 5(2) World Trade Rev. 177–98 (2006). 61 CRPD, supra note 1, at Article 32. Beyond the Orthodoxy of Rule of Law and Justice Sector Reform 59 Reasonable Accommodation as a Primary Means of Rights Facilitation One of the most important facilitators of the rights recognized in the CRPD is the concept of required reasonable accommodation. The failure to provide reasonable accommodation to an individual with a disability, whether to facil- itate access to education, work, health care, cultural activities, or other spheres of life, constitutes discrimination. Reasonable accommodation is being implemented at the domestic level in numerous ways. One example of using the tools of legal empowerment to equip persons with disabilities and employers to better understand how to operationalize reasonable accommodation is the Job Accommodation Net- work, an initiative of the Office of Disability Employment Policy in the US Department of Labor. The Job Accommodation Network is a model for the provision of free, expert, and confidential guidance on workplace accom- modations and disability employment issues.62 The service helps to identify practical solutions that benefit employers in meeting their reasonable accom- modations duties and employees in negotiating job accommodations. The ini- tiative focuses on workable solutions according to which legal requirements are satisfied within a framework that assists the employer and the employee in understanding legal requirements and measures that may be undertaken to meet them. This approach and similar initiatives are being operationalized as countries implement the obligations set forth in the CRPD. Other applica- tions of reasonable accommodation under development pertain to the obli- gations set forth in Article 12 to facilitate empowered decision making. Law reform initiatives in Ireland and South Africa, for example, are putting into place models that will reasonably accommodate individuals with disabilities in decision making about all aspects of life, including medical and rehabilita- tion issues, financial and property matters, and political participation.63 Improving Monitoring and Enforcement of Disability Rights National legislation, strategies, policies, and plans should provide for mecha- nisms and institutions that effectively address the individual and the struc- tural nature of the harm caused by disability discrimination and inequality of access to rights in all fields covered by the CRPD. Institutions dealing with allegations of disability discrimination customarily include courts and tribu- nals, administrative authorities, national human rights institutions, and om- budspersons. These institutions should be accessible to all persons with dis- abilities without discrimination and consistent with principles of accessibility. 62 See Job Accommodation Network, http://askjan.org/ (accessed Jul. 24, 2012). 63 For a discussion of the Irish initiative, see Amnesty International Ireland, Mental Health Act 2001: A Review, Summary Paper (undated). For a review of the South African effort to draft legislation on supported decision making, see South African Law Reform Commis- sion, Current Investigations, Progress Report, available at http://www.justice.gov.za/salrc /progress.htm. http://askjan.org/ http://www.justice.gov.za/salrc/progress.htm http://www.justice.gov.za/salrc/progress.htm The World Bank Legal Review60 Institutions should be empowered to provide effective remedies, such as com- pensation, reparation, restitution, rehabilitation, guarantees of nonrepetition, and public apologies, and states parties should ensure that these measures are effectively implemented. Improving Access to Dispute-Settlement Mechanisms The drafters of the CRPD understood the barriers that exist for persons with disabilities in seeking access to justice for the vindication of their rights. Some of these barriers parallel those that all marginalized groups experience and that contribute toward disempowerment, while others are more specific to disability. There is an overall lack of awareness or unintended insensitivity to disability-related concerns and needs among court personnel, including in- flexible court policies, practices, and procedures and inaccessible public infor- mation about courts and court services. Given recognition that access to justice programs for marginalized groups is essential and must be pursued in conjunction with top-down justice sector reform strategies, there are numerous possibilities for the use of existing plat- forms to enhance disability inclusion. In Afghanistan, Global Rights partnered with local women’s organizations and several universities to establish legal assistance bureaus in order to enhance women’s access to family courts and justice.64 Improving the accessibility of these courts to women, persons with disabilities, and other marginalized groups is essential to create well-trodden pathways for the enforcement of legal rights. DPOs are working to ensure that such community-based legal services are accessible to persons with dis- abilities. This is consistent with measures set forth in Article 13 of the CRPD. Eliminating Barriers through Litigation Legal empowerment approaches stress not only top-down training of judges and lawyers but also how to work within civil society to build capacity to en- gage in a range of activities that enhance and facilitate access to justice. Strate- gic litigation at the local level and through regional as well as international hu- man rights mechanisms is an effective tool for change provided it is designed and implemented by local organizations and not driven by ill-informed out- siders. Experience with existing domestic disability laws and existing regional systems discloses the possibilities for change. Antidiscrimination legislation with remedial measures is a tool that can help ensure equality and fair treatment in the face of continuing stigma and negative attitudes toward people with disabilities. In the United States, the Americans with Disabilities Act (ADA)65 has significantly affected the ability of persons with disabilities to combat stigma and discrimination in the work- 64 See Global Rights, Afghanistan, http://www.globalrights.org/site/PageServer?pagename =www_asia_afghanistan (accessed Jul. 25, 2012). 65 See, generally, P. Blanck et al., Disability Rights Law and Policy: Casebook (Thomson/West 2009). http://www.globalrights.org/site/PageServer?pagename=www_asia_afghanistan http://www.globalrights.org/site/PageServer?pagename=www_asia_afghanistan Beyond the Orthodoxy of Rule of Law and Justice Sector Reform 61 place. Consider the case of Don Perkl, an individual with intellectual disability, who was fired from Chuck E. Cheese, a pizza restaurant, because of his disabil- ity.66 Despite support from his supervisor and his coworkers, he was fired by a regional manager who believed that Perkl was threatening to the restaurant patrons due to his disability and unfit for the job. A jury disagreed, awarding Perkl back pay, legal fees, and compensatory damages under the ADA, as well as US$13 million in punitive damages, to deliver a strong message.67 Without the ADA for recourse, Perkl would have faced severe difficulty in challenging the regional manager for blatant disability-based discrimination. Across the globe, lawyers are undertaking similar cases in areas of disabil- ity rights. This work, including development projects that aim to strengthen the ability of civil society and legal aid clinics to undertake legal empower- ment work, must target the elimination of systemic disability discrimination and segregation that inhibit equitable access to all rights for persons with disabilities. The Harvard Law School Project on Disability, for example, has served as amici in a number of cases before the European Court of Human Rights, as well as the European Committee of Social Rights.68 Innovations in Monitoring: Disability Rights Budget Analysis Standard rule of law approaches overemphasize legal interventions that not only are top-down and disconnected from the marginalized groups that legal frameworks are intended to serve but also privilege practices that emphasize court-focused action over other equally valid and in some instances more ef- fective forms of interventions for marginalized groups. Legal empowerment approaches increasingly point to the efficacy of budgetary analysis as an im- portant tool in bringing legal obligations to bear on government action.69 In this regard, the CRPD sets up a framework that brings such approaches with- in its aperture. The CRPD conceptualizes nondiscrimination and equality and encom- passes a cross-cutting obligation that may be realized only through its appli- cation to specific substantive human rights, whether civil, political, economic, social, or cultural. It asserts a substantive equality approach that goes beyond formal equality and advances socially, economically, and historically margin- alized groups.70 Moreover, the CRPD is an affront to the discredited notion 66 See P. Blanck, Americans with Disabilities and Their Civil Rights: Past, Present, and Future, 66 U. Pitt. L. Rev. 687–719 (2006), for a discussion of this and other ADA cases in which Blanck was involved as an expert witness and legal counsel. 67 Id. 68 See Alajos Kiss v. Hungary, App. No. 38832/06 (Eur. Ct. of Human Rights, May 20, 2010), para- graph 4. 69 See Gillian MacNaughton & Paul Hunt, A Human Rights–Based Approach to Social Impact As- sessment, in New Directions in Social Impact Assessment: Conceptual and Methodological Advances 355, 360 (Frank Vanclay & Ana Maria Esteves ed., Edward Elgar 2012) (Budget analysis “re- veals human rights problems and affords means to tackle them”). 70 Janet E. Lord & Rebecca Brown, The Role of Reasonable Accommodation in Securing Substantive The World Bank Legal Review62 that civil and political rights require little in the way of positive action and in- vestment of resources by states in order to effect implementation.71 The CRPD brings the human rights framework together in requiring reasonable accom- modation through positive measures in all areas of life.72 The implications of this model for legal empowerment underscore the so- phistication of the CRPD framework. In projecting the need for a multifaceted approach to implementation, the CRPD embraces the need for budget analy- sis to track the extent to which states parties undertake the measures required to realize all rights under the CRPD, even those subject to progressive realiza- tion. Disability rights budget analysis encompasses an approach according to which a state party’s allocation of resources in a given area (for example, education, employment, or community living) is scrutinized and assessed.73 Budget analysis can be used to identify the sufficiency of resource allocation in an attempt to secure the rights of a particularly disadvantaged group.74 In this regard, the Limberg Principles on the Implementation of Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights75 stress that statistical information and information on budgetary allocations and expenditures should be presented in such a way as to facilitate the assessment of compliance with economic, social, and cultural rights obligations.76 Equality for Persons with Disabilities: The UN Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabili- ties, in Critical Perspectives on Human Rights and Disability Law 273 (Marcia Rioux, Lee Ann Basser, & Melinda Jones ed., Martinus Nijhoff 2011). 71 See Anna Lawson, Disability and Equality Law in Britain: The Role of Reasonable Adjustment (Hart 2008). 72 See Lord & Brown, supra note 70. 73 See Gillian MacNaughton, Human Rights Frameworks, Strategies, and Tools for the Poverty Law- yer’s Toolbox, J. Hum. Rights Prac. 83, 95. See also Janet E. Lord & Michael Ashley Stein, The Domestic Incorporation of Human Rights Law and the United Nations Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities, 83 Wash. L. Rev. 449, 459 (2008) (asserting that budget analysis in the disability rights context is an “essential component” of disability rights advocacy work). 74 S. Farrior, Human Rights Advocacy on Gender Issues: Challenges and Opportunities, 1 J. Hum. Rights Prac. 83– 100 (2009). See I. Diokno and M. Socorro, A Rights-Based Approach towards Budget Analysis 8 (International Human Rights Internship Program 1999), available at http://www .crin.org/docs/resources/publications/hrbap/RBABudgetAnalysis.pdf (accessed Feb. 22, 2012); Helena Hofbauer et al., Dignity Counts: A Guide to Using Budget Analysis to Advance Human Rights (International Budget Partnership 2004), available at http://www.iie.org /en/Programs/IHRIP/~/media/Files/Programs/IHRIP/Dignity_Counts.ashx (accessed Feb. 22, 2012). Budget analysis can also serve an important role in the realm of women’s rights. See, for example, Debbie Budlender & Rhonda Sharp, How to Do a Gender-Sensitive Budget Analysis: Contemporary Research and Practice (Commonwealth Secretariat 1998), available at http://www.thecommonwealth.org/shared_asp_files/uploadedfiles/%7B1171EF87-2C5C -4624-9D76-B03CF35F4E65%7D_AusAIDTr.pdf (accessed Feb. 22, 2012). 75 United Nations, Economic & Social Council, Limburg Principles on the Implementation of Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights, paragraph 79, UN Doc. E/CN.4/1987/17 ( Jan. 8, 1987). 76 Id. http://www.crin.org/docs/resources/publications/hrbap/RBABudgetAnalysis.pdf http://www.crin.org/docs/resources/publications/hrbap/RBABudgetAnalysis.pdf http://www.iie.org/en/Programs/IHRIP/~/media/Files/Programs/IHRIP/Dignity_Counts.ashx http://www.thecommonwealth.org/shared_asp_files/uploadedfiles/%7B1171EF87-2C5C-4624-9D76-B03CF35F4E65%7D_AusAIDTr.pdf http://www.iie.org/en/Programs/IHRIP/~/media/Files/Programs/IHRIP/Dignity_Counts.ashx http://www.thecommonwealth.org/shared_asp_files/uploadedfiles/%7B1171EF87-2C5C-4624-9D76-B03CF35F4E65%7D_AusAIDTr.pdf Beyond the Orthodoxy of Rule of Law and Justice Sector Reform 63 Inclusive Development Monitoring, Indicators, and Benchmarks States parties are obliged to monitor the implementation of measures to com- ply with CRPD obligations. Monitoring should assess both the steps taken and the results achieved in the elimination of barriers to effective access. National strategies, policies, and plans should use appropriate indicators and bench- marks in operationalizing the CRPD. Monitoring and evaluation practitioners have made significant advances in developing performance indicators to sim- plify the task of monitoring and evaluating human rights implementation and development interventions. Although most countries have a long way to go before they have effective monitoring and evaluation in the realm of disability and other areas, many are establishing monitoring and evaluation working groups comprising representatives from government, donor agencies, civil so- ciety, the UN system, and academic institutions. These groups seek to identify and adapt the indicators appropriate for their countries and to harmonize the collection, analysis, and reporting of data. As the first human rights convention to explicitly call upon states parties to reform their development assistance programs to include people with dis- abilities, the CRPD provides an important impetus for international coopera- tion and assistance. Considerable effort must be taken to ensure that donor governments and recipient developing countries adhere to the inclusive de- velopment mandate. This is unlikely to be achieved through the vehicle of na- tional disability legislative reform, but instead must be implemented through the adoption and monitoring of development policies. Participation in devel- opment decision making is a major focus of many DPO capacity-building en- deavors, and is reflected in the Australian Agency for International Develop- ment Disability Strategy, along with other donor initiatives. Groups such as Handicap International have worked to ensure that development tools, such as the processes to develop poverty reduction strategy papers in developing countries, are inclusive and conducted in collaboration and consultation with local DPOs. Looking Forward The CRPD provides a conceptual model for the legal empowerment of per- sons with disabilities through innovative and broad-based interventions. Its obligations are to be implemented through actions required by the mecha- nisms familiar to the rule of law orthodoxy. Moreover, beyond law and policy change, CRPD obligations are to be applied through culture building, partici- patory and empowering engagement in decision making, inclusive develop- ment practices, disability rights education, rights-based budget analysis, and other activities. The CRPD calls upon states, as well as development actors and DPOs, to engage in a variety of human rights actions in order to realize its implementation—from scoping exercises that examine accessibility obliga- tions in law and policy to law reform, law development, and human rights education that raises awareness among a wide array of stakeholders. The World Bank Legal Review64 The CRPD embodies the potential for a significant transformation in dis- ability legislation, policies, and programs around the world to empower per- sons with disabilities through full and equal enjoyment of all human rights and fundamental freedoms. Many governments and development practi- tioners realize this necessity, but do not have adequate knowledge of effec- tive practices and solutions. The CRPD addresses this concern prominently through Article 32, which highlights the role that capacity building, technical assistance, and the exchange of evidence-based knowledge and best practices can play in facilitating the changes that may be required after ratification. In- tellectual assistance plays a role, as does monetary assistance to support ac- tions by low- and middle-income countries to put the convention into practice. Article 32 encourages financial assistance to aid in CRPD implementation through inclusive and accessible aid programming. When international devel- opment addresses disability only as a separate issue distinct from mainstream programs, the result is a vicious circle where individuals with disabilities are further excluded and marginalized from the benefits of most economic and social development reforms and actions.77 Hence, Article 32 is critical to as- sist states parties in meeting their obligations under the CRPD and requires strong international cooperation. The international development community, together with the international disability rights community, can play a signifi- cant role in assisting states parties to reform their laws, policies, and programs to implement the CRPD by strengthening technical assistance, providing fi- nancial support to implement the articles of the convention, and exchanging knowledge on best practices. Article 32 requires states parties to work with each other and with relevant organizations to support capacity building “through the exchange and sharing of information, experiences, training pro- grammes and best practices” and to “facilitate cooperation in research and access to scientific and technical knowledge.” Knowledge and practices can be exchanged via networks that encour- age dialogue and collaboration through multiple communication strategies among researchers in academic institutions, think tanks, and governments across geographic regions. Participants in such networks can share findings from their activities that increase awareness and understanding about people with disabilities in areas such as deinstitutionalization and community living, employment and economic empowerment, legal capacity, human rights, and access to health care, education, and technology. One example of such a network is the Global Forum on Law, Justice and Development (GFLJD), initiated by the World Bank’s Legal Vice Presidency together with a number of academic and institutional partners from around the world. The GFLJD aims to bring together stakeholders in the fields of law, justice, and development, combining the economic, legal, and technical as- pects of a range of targeted issues beyond disability. By introducing disability into this network, practitioners can work toward mainstreaming the needs of 77 Samant, Matter, & Harniss, supra note 45. Beyond the Orthodoxy of Rule of Law and Justice Sector Reform 65 persons with disabilities across the spectrum of law, justice, and development programs around the world. The approaches to legal empowerment and innovation called for in the implementation of the CRPD can be built upon to advance an emerging dis- ability rights narrative with roots at the community as well as national level. Empowerment and innovation will be achieved in these reform efforts only with the full participation of and meaningful consultation with persons with disabilities and their representative organizations. The Political Economy of Improving Traditional Justice Systems A Case Study of NGO Engagement with Shalish in Bangladesh Stephen Golub In the past decade, the role that traditional justice systems (TJSs) play in the lives of the rural poor has received increasing attention.1 Sometimes referred to as customary justice systems, nonstate justice systems (because they have not originated as legal systems devised and administered by the state), or al- ternative dispute resolution (when viewed as alternatives to the courts), TJSs handle most disputes and other justice processes in many societies, particu- larly in rural areas. Across the globe, institutions such as development agencies, national gov- ernments, and civil society groups are exploring whether and how to work with TJSs. TJSs merit this focus because they are so central to the lives of so many. Yet, they often are blatantly unfair to women and other populations who suffer from power imbalances in their disputes and in their lives. The powerful can use TJSs as a mechanism to control the relatively powerless. They are often instruments, then, for the administration not just of justice but also, informally, of local governance. With these considerations in mind, what can and should development, government, and civil society institutions do to help make TJSs more equitable in their operations? This chapter aims to address this question by examining how NGOs in Bangladesh attempt to employ, modify, or monitor the country’s main TJS, known as shalish, so as to retain its meritorious features and ameliorate its drawbacks.2 Most Bangladeshi NGOs seek to make shalish less gender biased, corrupt, and punitive, as well as fairer and more accountable. As with any customary system, the way shalish functions varies among communities 1 The World Bank, the UK Department for International Development (DfID), the United Nations Development Programme (UNDP), and the International Development Law Or- ganization are but a few of the major international agencies conducting relevant research, programs, or other initiatives. 2 This chapter draws on the author’s numerous visits to Bangladesh between 1993 and 2012 in the course of consulting for DfID, the Asia Foundation, the Asian Development Bank, the Ford Foundation, and other internationally oriented organizations, as well as additional research conducted by the author. 67 The World Bank Legal Review68 and regions. However, the picture painted with broad strokes in this chapter applies to much of the country. The TJS operations of Bangladeshi NGOs take on additional salience for the international community in view of the recently launched the Community Legal Services Programme, which will support such work (as well as related, justice-oriented activities). Funded by the United Kingdom Department for International Development (DfID), this five-year (2012–17), 17 million GBP initiative will provide a substantial base of experience and research that other development institutions and countries can draw on.3 This chapter first delves into the importance of TJSs. It then discusses the nature of shalish in its conventional, unmodified form, unaffected by NGO in- fluence. It moves on to address NGO efforts to improve shalish operations or to act as substitutes for the process. Finally, the chapter offers some reflections on the implications of this analysis for international development, including for NGOs and governments concerned with customary justice. The political economy approach taken in this discussion mirrors the strat- egies of many NGOs seeking to improve shalish. Traditional justice is not just about dispute resolution. It is also about power, politics, governance, gender, community dynamics, and resource allocation. Any approach to justice and development that relies mainly on technical analyses and solutions is bound to fall far short of the mark in its attempts to formulate, promote, and implement reforms. This kind of approach is es- pecially misguided in the case of customary justice. For instance, an NGO or government program that trains traditional leaders how to mediate intra- community conflicts addresses a minor or nonexistent need. That organiza- tion or program should instead focus on the economic, political, and cultural influences and incentives that shape the behaviors of community leaders and members alike. To their considerable credit, many Bangladeshi NGOs do exactly that in grappling with the considerable challenge of improving shalish. In taking this tack, these NGOs take a legal empowerment approach to working with traditional justice. That is, the NGOs use the law (in this case, customary law) and rights (involving gender equity, for example) specifically to help the disadvantaged gain greater control over their lives. The Global Context: The Main Way the Poor Seek Justice DfID has estimated that “in many developing countries, traditional or cus- tomary legal systems account for 80 percent of total cases.”4 The Development Assistance Committee of the Organisation for Economic Co-operation and 3 See http://www.communitylegalservice.org/index.php (accessed Sep. 28, 2012). 4 DfID, Safety, Security and Accessible Justice: Putting Policy into Practice 58 (undated). http://www.communitylegalservice.org/index.php The Political Economy of Improving Traditional Justice Systems 69 Development (OECD) similarly points to research suggesting that “non-state systems are the main providers of justice and security for up to 80 –90 percent of the population” in fragile states.5 These calculations reflect the fact that, by virtue of choice or necessity, the poor in many societies use customary forums to seek justice more than they do formal governmental institutions, especially in rural areas. Why is this the case? Due to cost, inconvenience, incomprehensibility, or corruption, justice through judiciaries (and other state institutions) can be dif- ficult or impossible for poor people to access. Even where access to justice through state institutions is feasible, it is not necessarily the preferred option. In the relatively rare instances where free legal aid is available and effec- tive, the act of going to court can be an expensive one. It can involve court fees and other expenses, and repeated court visits can drain a great deal of time away from earning a living. Going to court also can be inconvenient, due to those repeated visits and the great distances that the rural poor must travel for trials and other legal proceedings. Once a plaintiff is in court, the proceedings may be incomprehensible, often conducted in languages (such as those of the nations’ former colonial rulers) that may be foreign to him or her. In addition, legal discourse is highly technical and beyond the grasp of even educated nonlawyers, not to mention the illiterate or impoverished. Finally, there is no guarantee that judicial proceedings are free from corruption, political control, gender biases, or other undue influences that undercut their fairness, particu- larly for the poor. None of this is to deny the value of well-functioning courts for many pur- poses, not least addressing serious crimes, human rights abuses, and public policy issues. Nor is it to claim that TJSs always operate fairly; as already em- phasized here, that is far from the case. But the fact that a well-functioning judiciary is desirable does not mean it is achievable. Efforts to address judi- cial inadequacies have proven problematic in many nations, including Ban- gladesh. Notwithstanding the presence of some fine Bangladeshi jurists, the country’s court system has been resistant to change. A 2011 World Bank re- port, Disputes, Crimes and Pathways of Redress: A Household Survey on Citizens’ Perceptions and Experiences of the Justice System in Bangladesh, indicates wide- spread lack of public confidence in the courts, police, and other formal justice sector institutions.6 In terms of cost, convenience, and comprehensibility, TJSs do have distinct advantages over the courts. The poor do not have to pay to use them. TJSs usu- ally take far less time than court cases do, even if they do not always offer in- stant justice. Their dispute-resolution sessions typically take place much closer 5 OECD/DAC Network on Conflict, Peace and Development Co-operation, Enhancing the De- livery of Justice and Security in Fragile States 4 (Aug. 2006). 6 Saku Akmeemana, Disputes, Crimes and Pathways of Redress: A Household Survey on Citizens’ Perceptions and Experiences of the Justice System in Bangladesh (World Bank 2011). The World Bank Legal Review70 to where the poor reside. TJS proceedings are conducted in languages that the poor understand and are often conducted by fellow community members. Being more comprehensible and rooted in their communities can make some TJSs more transparent and accountable to the poor—at least compared with incomprehensible judicial systems that leave the poor open to manipula- tion by judges, court personnel, or even their own attorneys. Nevertheless, although TJSs may be preferable to the courts for many purposes, that fact constitutes faint praise. Conventional Shalish: An Overview The term shalish (or salish) refers to a traditional, community-based, largely informal Bangladeshi process through which small, loosely constituted panels of influential local figures help resolve community members’ disputes and/ or impose sanctions on them. The term is applied in at least four ways: to the process in general, to an individual hearing, to a series of hearings about a specific dispute, and to the panel conducting a hearing. The panel members are called shalishdars. Although practiced across most of the country, shalish is not the only lo- cal, informal method of dispute resolution in Bangladesh. Cultural minorities employ their own, varied methods. As in many societies, Bangladeshi dis- putants may seek out influential individuals for advice or decisions without turning to a panel of such persons. But the widespread use and diverse forms of shalish make it potentially fertile ground for international efforts to under- stand analogous processes and external efforts to improve them. Shalish may involve voluntary submission to arbitration (which, in this context, involves the parties agreeing to submit to the judgment of the shalish panel) or mediation (in which the panel helps the disputants devise a settle- ment themselves). Frequently, shalish blends the two, such that the two par- ties are nominally free to accept or reject shalishdars’ recommendations, but pressure from the shalishdars or other community members may undermine the voluntariness of such decisions. A harsh (though relatively rare) version of shalish can take a punitive form. In such instances, the forum constitutes a de facto criminal court that inflicts trial and punishment on individuals who have not consented to its jurisdiction. With the exception of the summary judgment imposed under that harsh version, a shalish can result in a quick resolution or may extend over numer- ous sessions and months. Negotiations between disputants, often including or represented by family members, sometimes also take place outside these sessions, complementing the discussions that take place within them. The term “dispute-resolution process” suggests calm deliberation, with the parties patiently putting forth their perspectives and impartial facilitators The Political Economy of Improving Traditional Justice Systems 71 soberly sorting through the issues. Although not the product of a scientific survey, this author’s impressions of more than a dozen (NGO-organized) sha- lish sessions during the 1990s were rather different: The actual shalish is often a loud and passionate event in which disputants, relatives, [shalish panel] members and even uninvited community members congregate to express their thoughts and feel- ings. Additional observers—adults and children alike—gather in the room’s doorway and outside. More than one exchange of opinions may occur simultaneously. Calm discussions explode into bursts of shouting and even laughter or tears. All of this typically takes place in a crowded school room or other public space, sweltering most of the year, often with the noise of other community activities filter- ing in from outside. The number of participants and observers may range from a few dozen to well over one hundred.7 Even more significant, it can be misleading to characterize shalish as con- stituting alternative dispute resolution. As Siddiqi explains: The shalish should not be thought of as an alternative [emphasis in original] dispute resolution mechanism in Bangladesh. The concept of Alternative Dispute Resolution (ADR) was developed in relation to a specific set of needs within various “western” legal systems. While many features of ADR are similar to those that characterize the shalish, the latter does not by any means constitute an alterna- tive for the vast majority of the rural population. Indeed, despite its visibility and prominence, available statistics would argue for view- ing the formal justice system as the “alternative” form of dispute resolution.8 Siddiqi’s insight applies to most disputes involving most rural Bangla- deshis and many urban ones. Even if the country’s problematic courts oper- ated more efficiently and equitably, they still would represent an alternative to shalish, rather than vice versa. The Main Types of Disputes Addressed via Shalish Shalish most commonly addresses two types of disputes: one category in- volves family and gender issues; the other involves property, including land and petty theft. Gender/family disputes can pertain to dowry (the price, in cash or kind, that the bride’s family typically pays that of the groom), dower/denmohor (a payment that the groom may promise the bride but that she usually forgoes 7 Stephen Golub, From the Village to the University: Legal Activism in Bangladesh, in Many Roads to Justice: The Law-Related Work of Ford Foundation Grantees around the World 137 –38 (Mary McClymont & Stephen Golub ed., Ford Foundation 2000). 8 D. M. Siddiqi, Shalish and the Quest for Gender Justice: An Assessment of Strategic Interventions in Bangladesh, report prepared for Research Initiatives, Bangladesh, 11 (Mar. 17, 2004). The World Bank Legal Review72 unless he divorces her), maintenance payments (for a wife’s and children’s ex- penses in the event of separation or divorce), polygamy, “torture” (a term that usually refers to physical or psychological abuse, such as by the husband’s family against the wife, rather than to protracted infliction of pain for pur- poses of sadism or interrogation), and divorce. Given the nature of Bangladeshi households and family structures, many such disputes are not confined to two individuals. Entire families often become involved and may even instigate conflict. In such instances, not all mistreat- ment is by men against women. A husband’s mother may be the lead actor in abuses against his wife. And gender-related power imbalances notwithstand- ing, there certainly are instances in which women treat men unfairly. That being said, abusive treatment of women cuts across many gender- related disputes. This can involve both physical and psychological mistreat- ment (the latter sometimes called “mental torture”). Young women who are taken into the homes of in-laws after marriage may be especially victimized in this way. The new wives are often just girls.9 Such abuse often is linked to ongoing dowry demands by the husband’s family. Dowry does not appear deeply rooted in the history of the lands that be- came Bangladesh. White10 and Rozario11 both suggest that dowry dates back only several decades at most, and that previously it was common for the hus- band’s family to pay that of the wife in connection with a wedding. Why dowry has become dominant is a matter of conjecture. Geirbo and Imam discuss an array of possible economic, social, and historical causes—including supply and demand for husbands versus wives—but do not draw firm conclusions.12 In any case, dowry triggers or is otherwise related to gender disputes be- cause it involves demands by the husband or his parents for payments by the wife’s parents. The convention must be seen in the context of a society in which poorly educated girls are viewed as economic liabilities; families may be anxious to see daughters wed because (if the families are impoverished) they represent extra mouths to feed and/or marriages may represent a road to the families’ social advancement; and girls and their families may be socially ostracized if they remain single. As with gender-related disputes, land conflicts blend with other societal issues. They are embedded in the nature of the society’s poverty, structure, 9 In one area studied by the Bangladeshi Rural Advancement Committee (BRAC) and the Population Council, 80 percent of brides were under 18 years old. BRAC and Population Council, Bangladesh Adolescent Survey 2004 (Dhaka 2004). 10 S. White, Arguing with the Crocodile: Class and Gender Hierarchies in a Bangladeshi Village 102 (U. Press Limited 1992). 11 S. Rozario, Purity and Communal Boundaries: Women and Social Change in a Bangladeshi Village 131–35 (U. Press Limited 2001). 12 H. C. Geirbo & N. Imam, The Motivations behind Giving and Taking Dowry, Research Mono- graph Series No. 28, 2 –3 (BRAC Research and Evaluation Division Jul. 2006). The Political Economy of Improving Traditional Justice Systems 73 and agrarian constraints.13 Problems involving land are not always distinct from gender matters, and they may be intrafamily in nature. Conventional Shalish as Both Dispute Resolution and Social Control Before considering efforts to modify shalish, it is important to consider what shalish constitutes in its conventional, traditional form. As summarized by Khair, traditional shalish is basically a practice of gathering village elders and concerned par- ties, exclusively male, for the resolution of local disputes. Sometimes Chairmen and elite members of the Union Parishad [a local govern- ment unit] are invited to sit through the proceedings. Shalish has no fixed dimension and its size and structure depend entirely on the nature and gravity of the problem at hand.14 A shalish may be completed in one day, but it may extend over a number of sessions and involve private negotiations between disputants, often encom- passing their families. Traditional shalish may inappropriately and illegally handle even the most serious criminal actions, including rape. Whether a specific shalish constitutes mediation or arbitration, or a blend of the two, hinges on the dynamics at play. Community mores and the opin- ions of powerful leaders often exert such strong influences that outcomes are imposed on a disputant contrary to his or her wishes. In the alternative, the disputant may have a nominal choice, but pressure to act in accord with mores and opinions effectively forces acquiescence. Thus, a woman victimized by domestic violence may be forced to return to her husband because the shalish- dars tolerate such treatment and because they chastise the husband only in a pro forma manner. Khair and her colleagues highlight some of the problems afflicting con- ventional shalish: Sometimes solutions are arbitrary and imposed on reluctant dispu- tants by powerful village or community members. Such “solutions” are based less on civil or other law than on subjective judgments designed to ensure the continuity of their leadership, to strengthen their relational alliances, or to uphold the perceived cultural norms and biases. The shalish also is susceptible to manipulation by corrupt touts [persons who exploit some nominal knowledge of the law] and local musclemen who may be hired to guide the pace and direction of the process by intimidation. Furthermore, because the traditional 13 See, for example, E. G. Jansen, Rural Bangladesh: Competition for Scarce Resources (Norwegian U. Press 1987). 14 S. Khair, Alternative Approaches to Justice: A Review of ADR Initiatives under the Democracy Part- nership, report prepared for the Asia Foundation, 5 (May 2001). The World Bank Legal Review74 shalish is composed exclusively of male members, women are par- ticularly vulnerable to extreme judgments and harsh penalties.15 One additional, crucial dimension of traditional shalish that must be emphasized is its role as an institution for perpetuating the social control of women and the poor. Hashmi explicates this point when describing the “member-matbar-mulla” triumvirate that controls village affairs, including shalish: The members of the Union Parishad (the lowest electoral unit) are elected officials, in charge of the disbursement of public goods and relief materials among the poor villagers, and are the most powerful in the triumvirate. They are often connected with the ruling political party of other influential power-brokers in the neighboring towns or groups of villages. The matbars (matabbars) or village elders, who also sit on the salish (village court), are next in the hierarchy, hav- ing vested interests in the village economy as rentiers and money- lenders. They often get shares in misappropriated relief goods along with government officials and members-chairmen of the Union Pari- shads. The mulla, associated with the local mosques and maktabs (el- ementary religious schools), are sometimes quite influential as they endorse the activities of village elders albeit in the name of Islamic or Sharia law. They often sit on the salish and issue fatwas in support of their patrons, the village elders. The rural poor, often women, are victims of these fatwas.16 The increasing involvement of women and younger political figures in village affairs may run counter to the bleak picture painted here. However, with the increased politicization of society involving armed thugs, these influences are further tainting traditional shalish, according to a number of sources.17 Why, then, do Bangladeshis still turn to traditional shalish to address their disputes? The reasons echo the reality that customary justice systems are often favored by the poor across the globe. Thus, although otherwise highly critical of the institution, Siddiqi notes: For poor villagers, especially women, the shalish offers many advan- tages. First, a shalish hearing does not require any serious expendi- ture. Second, it takes place locally, at a time that is convenient for all of the parties involved. Proceedings occur in a language and frame- 15 S. Khair et al., Access to Justice: Best Practices under the Democracy Partnership 8–9 (Asia Foun- dation, Apr. 2002). 16 T. Hashmi, Women and Islam in Bangladesh: Beyond Subjection and Tyranny 137 (Macmillan 2000). 17 For a summary of recent scholarship concerning these trends, see Harry Blair, Civil Society, Dispute Resolution and Local Governance in Bangladesh: Ideas for Pro-Poor Programme Support, report prepared for the Department for International Development, UK High Commission (May 2003). The Political Economy of Improving Traditional Justice Systems 75 work of justice that is comprehensible to the litigants. Third, disputes are resolved relatively quickly, usually in one to three sittings.18 The bottom line is that shalish is often the first and only choice available to impoverished Bangladeshis. It is affordable, comprehensible, convenient, and efficient, even in contrast with a well-functioning judicial system—not to mention the country’s courts. Efforts to modify conventional shalish, then, should not be seen simply in terms of improving dispute resolution or access to justice. To the consider- able degree that traditional shalish perpetuates poverty and the poor’s lack of control over their lives, efforts to reform it can contribute to the fundamental development goals of poverty alleviation and good governance. The Punitive Approach: Shalish as Trial From time to time, harshly punitive versions of traditional shalish have been reported. These reports describe incidents of people being lashed or even stoned to death for violation of local norms. The reports, which received at- tention from Amnesty International in the 1990s,19 have attracted significant attention in the Bangladeshi press over the years. The kind of shalish documented in these reports goes far beyond media- tion or even arbitration and amounts to de facto trials. These trials result in fatwas decreed by mullas who belong to the shalish panels or otherwise influ- ence them. The mullas interpret or misinterpret sharia to subject the “defen- dants” to horrible punishment that exceeds the more mundane (though still unfair) edicts described by Hashmi. While egregious, these punitive shalish processes appear to be relatively rare. According to a 2006–07 study conducted by the Asia Foundation for DfID: Only a few NGOs consulted in the study had even heard of such abuses taking place anywhere close to their areas of operation. Even then, their responses to questions about the practice suggest that the few dozen newspaper reports of the abuses may represent the sum total of the problem rather than a window on a problem that is more prevalent than reports would suggest. This is also the opinion of ASK [Ain O Salish Kendra, a women’s rights NGO discussed in fur- ther detail below], which tracks violations of this kind. Local and na- tional NGOs are sometimes able to mobilize police to prevent such actions before they occur.20 18 D. M. Siddiqi, Paving the Way to Justice: The Experience of Nagorik Uddyog, Bangladesh 10 (One World Action 2005). 19 See, for example, Amnesty International, Bangladesh: Taking the Law in Their Own Hands: The Village Salish (ASA Dec. 13, 1993). 20 Asia Foundation, Promoting Improved Access to Justice: Community Legal Service Delivery in Bangladesh 22 (Asia Foundation, Mar. 2007). The World Bank Legal Review76 This is not to minimize the threat that punitive shalish could become if it were to grow in rural areas, particularly given the increasing influence of ultraconservative religious elements in some parts of the country in recent years. At this point, however, the problem seems to be severe in nature but limited in scope. Four Prominent Approaches to Modifying Shalish There appear to be four main approaches that NGOs take to modify shalish.21 NGOs Organize Shalish Possibly the most common form of NGO interaction with shalish occurs when an NGO organizes shalish panels and sessions, sometimes building on other rights-oriented or development-oriented activities it has undertaken in the community. NGOs are able to take such initiatives for varying reasons, includ- ing their long-standing presence and credibility in a community, the influence they derive from their other operations, and in some cases their success at co- opting traditional shalishdars. Much of this approach is derived from the pioneering efforts of the Madaripur Legal Aid Association (MLAA, named for the district in which it mainly works). MLAA’s work reaches back nearly 30 years. In addition to its own direct engagement with shalish, MLAA provides lawyers to assist clients when necessary (such as when they are victims of violent crimes) and trains NGOs from across the country in its approach. The nature and degree of NGO engagement with shalish varies consid- erably. NGOs such as MLAA and Nagorik Uddyog (NU) may include tra- ditional shalishdars in the new panels in order to maintain the presence of influential persons. But they supplement them with educated persons (such as teachers) who may have broader and less-traditional perspectives, women from various backgrounds, and men who may be relatively uneducated or impoverished. Once the NGO convenes a shalish, its own personnel may play passive roles at the session, with the shalishdars managing the mediation. There are distinct differences among organizations taking this approach. MLAA is distinguished by a fairly extensive network of personnel covering a district (and nearby areas) of more than 1 million people and close, longstand- ing connections with the local bar associations. The community-based organi- zations it forms are mainly shalish panels. In contrast, the Bangladesh National Women Lawyers Association (BNWLA) works with partner NGOs that in turn train community members 21 Although the author has been able to update the information upon which he bases this sec- tion via correspondence and three 2012 visits to Bangladesh, much of the analysis in this section draws on research conducted five or more years ago. It is possible that the nature of the engagement of certain NGOs with shalish changed during the intervening period. The Political Economy of Improving Traditional Justice Systems 77 to conduct shalish. Unlike with MLAA, BNWLA personnel do not attend sha- lish sessions, but representatives from partner NGOs do. NU organizes and trains shalish panels on a local (ward) level, requiring that at least one-third of the shalishdars be women. NU then draws on these panels to form higher-level (Union Parishad) legal aid committees that both review shalish outcomes and monitor the more general human rights situa- tion in their areas. Unlike BNWLA and MLAA, NU does not include attorneys on its staff. Like NU, the women’s development NGO Banchte Shekha, which in many respects is also a membership organization, often plays active and di- verse roles with respect to its partner populations. It is active, for instance, in the areas of livelihood, credit, health, education, and other gender-oriented work. Many years of efforts to improve women’s perspectives, knowledge, financial well-being, and status bolster the NGO’s local credibility and influ- ence in its approach to shalish. Its shalish panels are accordingly more heavily weighted with untraditional shalishdars, especially women, drawn from its partner populations. Its personnel play active roles in suggesting and even directing shalish deliberations. Although there is no typical model for NGO-organized shalish, Hasle pro- vides a useful summary of a process employed by NU. She bears quoting at some length, for she illustrates the many stages of the organization’s engage- ment with the process: NU seeks out members of the traditional shalish that are open to a more democratic and just form of dispute resolution—as identified through participatory local level workshops—and invites them to become members of a local NU shalish committee, along with other individuals representing a cross-section of the community. One third of the members are women, and a particular effort is made to in- clude women Union members [i.e., women who have been elected to the local Union Parishad, or governing council]. As a matter of strategy, NU seek[s] to transform rather than replace the existing power structure through a method of cooptation, and in particular by bringing together “influential” and ordinary (“non- influential”) members of the community in training and mediation, thereby fostering new allegiances. . . . Once established, NU aims to provide the committee members with necessary tools for promoting greater justice in the shalish process. Emphasis is given to education and training, combining human rights education with information about the law, including civil and criminal laws, as well as religious and customary laws. Committee members are also introduced to local lawyers who stand ready to assist them on a case-by-case basis. Role-plays and other forms of participatory exercises are used to enhance the members’ sensitivity to prevailing attitudes and norms that discriminate against women, and develop legal and moral arguments for how these can be coun- The World Bank Legal Review78 teracted through the shalish. Members of the shalish committee are not, however, on NU’s payroll, and are free to take part in the tradi- tional shalish in their own capacity. One of NU’s main activities is to organise shalish hearings (NU- shalish hereafter). These are convened on the basis of an applica- tion from an aggrieved member of the community, which is filed with one of NU’s Community Organisers (CO). COs are volunteers from the respective communities where NU operates, and each CO cover[s] one Union. All COs have received human rights and legal training from NU, and have access to local lawyers. When NU has accepted an application . . . the CO undertakes a fact- finding exercise, to verify the applicant’s claims and to collect other relevant information. Provided the application is considered valid (i.e. that the fact-finding confirms that there is a grievance), a formal notice inviting the respondent to a NU-shalish is sent. . . . It should be noted that NU would not convene a shalish in criminal cases, as a part of their strategy to promote greater respect for the rule of law; and would take action to ensure that these cases are adjudicated by formal courts, with assistance from NU as relevant. Assuming the respondent is willing to meet in a NU-shalish, a me- diation session is convened. While NU facilitates the mediation by organising the venue, NU staff plays a passive role in the discussion, which is led by members of the NU-shalish committee, representa- tives from NU’s women leadership programme and representatives from each of the parties (which may include non-NU shalishdars and other influential people). According to NU policy, a resolution should be reached through mediation and not arbitration. As discussed with project staff, this is understood to imply willingness to compromise on both sides, and while law is a relevant factor in the negotiation, it is not the only—or even the dominant—consideration. . . . Provided an agreement is reached, which is overwhelmingly the case, this is recorded in the minutes of the hearing, which is signed by both parties. . . . If the opposing party is unwilling to reach a settlement, or the applicant considers the settlement unreasonable, NU stands ready to provide legal aid to the applicant so as to facili- tate a formal court hearing. This is also an option in cases where the respondent does not abide by the decisions made. Following the mediation, NU undertakes to visit the applicant on a monthly basis for three months, so as to monitor the implementation of the shalish decision.22 A 2011 study of NU’s program to build up women’s leadership roles (in- cluding in shalish) provides a similarly positive assessment of the organiza- tion’s work: 22 Lena Hasle, Too Poor for Rights? Access to Justice for Poor Women in Bangladesh: A Case Study 10 –12 (unpublished MSC dissertation for the London School of Economics 2004). The Political Economy of Improving Traditional Justice Systems 79 [I]t seems that this programme is . . . a potentially useful model of a women’s leadership building strategy. . . . The efforts of Nagorik Uddyog appear to have resulted in perceptible expansion of wom- en’s political space (manifest in greater substantive participation in shalish) and in conjunction with other women’s empowerment strategies currently taking place in rural Bangladesh, such efforts could have a real, positive long-term impact on the status of women in Bangladeshi society.23 NGO-Assisted Community-Based Organizations (CBOs) Modify Shalish Some NGOs concentrate on strengthening partner community-based orga- nizations (CBOs) so that they can affect shalish.24 Part of the rationale is to strengthen access to justice while minimizing NGO engagement and com- munity dependence on NGOs. Under this approach, NGO personnel avoid involvement in creating panels and initiating sessions. They instead concen- trate on strengthening citizen capacities to join, pressure, persuade, educate, and otherwise influence traditional shalish bodies. The community mem- bers who are trained and supported by NGOs seek to influence preexisting shalish panels. To varying extents, NGOs engage in monitoring traditional shalish panels even as they seek to co-opt those panels or set up parallel structures. Ain O Salish Kendra (ASK), a women’s rights NGO, takes this approach. ASK trains and supports a number of other NGOs to help affiliated CBOs exert influence on shalish and on other local institutions and issues. One such partner orga- nization is the Bangladesh Rural Advancement Committee (BRAC), a very large national NGO that promotes livelihood development, microfinance, and numerous other socioeconomic initiatives in many parts of the country.25 Siddiqi summarizes key aspects of this approach, in terms of how ASK aids partner NGOs: The organization does not have any offices in the field but works through six [at the time of Siddiqi’s summary] partner NGOs. GSJP [ASK Gender and Social Justice Program] staff spend considerable time in the field but their mandate is strictly limited. They do not form alternative shalish committees, nor are they allowed to partici- pate in local shalish. Their role is to observe, to monitor and to per- suade. The GSJP seeks to monitor local shalish, track human rights violations in its working areas and increase the legal literacy of the 23 Ryan Higgitt, Women’s Leadership Building as a Poverty Reduction Strategy, 6(1) J. S. Asian Dev. 114 (2011). 24 To make a crude distinction between the two, NGOs are nonprofits that at least partly com- prise paid staff, whereas CBOs comprise members of the very populations they serve, repre- sent, or otherwise benefit. 25 In recent years, BRAC has branched out beyond Bangladesh to launch operations in other countries. The World Bank Legal Review80 local population. The strategy is to empower through knowledge. ASK focuses on legal education and empowerment in a general sense, working on the assumption that the desired effect on the sha- lish can be achieved only with an overall shift in ideology. With the help of its partner NGOs, ASK staff members in the field help to organize a Manobodhikar Songrokkhon Parishad (MSP) [Human Rights Protection Committee], previously known as Ain Shohayota Committees (ASC) [legal assistance committees]. [ASK and its partner NGOs also organize human rights committees exclu- sively comprising women.] As the name suggests, the responsibili- ties of MSP members are primarily to monitor the local situation, to intervene in cases where the law has been broken and to facilitate the spread of human rights information. Committee members basically have a watchdog capacity. Members are not necessary [sic] drawn from the dominant social groups, at least not exclusively. Through its Gender and Social Justice program, ASK seeks to chal- lenge and transform local knowledge and moral codes of conduct. The organization’s approach is quite distinct—unlike other NGOs involved in remaking the shalish, ASK does not intervene directly in shalish proceedings. Its objective is more long-term—it seeks to per- suade the inhabitants in its working areas of the need to transform the existing gendered and unequal structures of power.26 As Siddiqi further explains, “ASK proceeds on the assumption that an equitable and representative shalish structure can be created and sustained only when there is an overall shift in community norms and practices of power.”27 This point does not discount other organizations’ efforts to alter commu- nity dynamics so that women and other disadvantaged populations achieve greater power and more equitable treatment. The ASK approach aims for a lesser degree of NGO engagement so as to facilitate a greater degree of CBO empowerment. The ways in which such an approach plays out in practice vary among partner NGOs, but usually involve a degree of community organizing by the partner. Alim describes how one partner, BRAC, increased the power of its members by pulling them together into not just small-scale community orga- nizations but also larger-scale (but still local) federations that have a greater likelihood of exercising influence.28 Alim analyzes two examples of such operations. In one instance the fed- eration (with a woman leading the way) influenced the deliberations of a 26 Siddiqi, supra note 8. 27 D. M. Siddiqi, Ain O Salish Kendra: Twenty Years on the Frontline 34 (ASK Dec. 2006). 28 A. Alim, Shalish and the Role of BRAC’s Federation: Improving the Poor’s Access to Justice, Social Science Research Network Paper 905745 (2004), available at papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers .cfm?abstract_id=905745. www.papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=905745 papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers The Political Economy of Improving Traditional Justice Systems 81 shalish regarding an alleged petty theft. In the other, a case of a husband who had illegally taken a second wife, the federation sought police assistance when the shalish failed to reach a resolution. Specifically, this intervention prevented the husband from selling land and leaving his first wife and five children destitute.29 NGO Staff Members Conduct Shalish A number of NGOs utilize individual staff members to settle conflicts between disputants without the involvement of shalish panels. Such efforts—often also called shalish by such groups because of their mediation-oriented nature— can take a number of forms. In some instances, a field or office worker initially interviews one or more disputants and explores the other options of NGO-fa- cilitated shalish or litigation. In others, this kind of shalish is the main mecha- nism by which the NGO seeks to help resolve a dispute; the NGO retains the option of utilizing its own staff or outside counsel to pursue legal redress. Thus, at the same time that ASK aids partner NGOs and CBOs in modify- ing traditional shalish, its Dhaka-based personnel conduct shalish between disputants. Similarly, even as BRAC (sometimes with the assistance of ASK) seeks to strengthen the roles of its partner populations and CBOs in modifying traditional shalish and human rights in their communities, its staff members individually conduct shalish sessions. Bangladesh Legal Aid and Services Trust (BLAST), a national NGO that undertakes both individual legal aid and more policy-oriented litigation and advocacy, employs this approach exclusively. Staff members engage in shalish but do not become involved in organizing shalish panels or CBOs the way other NGOs’ staff members do. The BLAST approach also differs in that, un- like some other NGOs (that rely on outside counsel), BLAST can threaten a recalcitrant party with litigation on behalf of BLAST’s client if an agreement is not reached. Thus, BLAST is often closer to arbitration than mediation on the spectrum of what shalish effectively means. This is not to say that BLAST always takes the opposing party to court if shalish fails. But the threat is more immediate than for many other NGOs. NGOs Aid the Government’s Village Court System Bangladesh has made an effort to build on the advantages of shalish by insti- tuting a formal, officially recognized mediation system. First implemented de- cades ago, village courts are dispute-resolution bodies that have official status under the laws of Bangladesh30 but have been moribund in large parts of the country. In connection with the adoption of the Village Courts Act in 2006, there has been renewed donor and government interest in reviving these insti- 29 Id., at 42–43. 30 The 1961 Muslim Family Laws Ordinance is a precursor to the village courts. The 1976 Vil- lage Courts Ordinance put in place the legal structure that, except for raising the jurisdiction limit from 5,000 to 25,000 taka, largely stayed unchanged in the 2006 Village Courts Act. The World Bank Legal Review82 tutions. The United Nations Development Programme (UNDP), for example, is conducting a project aiming to “activate” village courts.31 Union Parishad chairpersons head village courts. Other Union Parishad members may substitute for them, however. In addition, with the permission of the chairperson, a nonmember may chair the five-person village court panel. The opposing sides of a dispute each select two of the other four members, in- cluding one Union Parishad member each. If two parties agree to the jurisdic- tion of a village court, they are bound by its decision if four out of the five pan- elists (or if one panelist is absent, three out of four members) agree on a ruling. In recent years, MLAA has played a role in trying to revive the institu- tion through training and advice. Certainly, Union Parishad chairpersons command a great deal of authority in their communities. Disputes, Crimes and Pathways of Redress indicates that community members often seek their help in resolving disputes even in the absence of village courts.32 Other NGOs are more skeptical about the village courts’ prospects for success. They base this skepticism on the long history of largely fruitless ef- forts to fortify institutions. They also are concerned about the village courts’ potentially politicized or corrupt nature. Other sources lend weight to these doubts by raising questions about local political dynamics, Union Parishad members’ biases, and the village courts themselves.33 Additional Research Findings As with so much in the field of law and development, there is a shortage of research that documents the impact of efforts to improve shalish. The studies cited in this chapter provide some preliminary evidence that NGO engage- ment with shalish can enhance equity in resolving disputes and improve the situations of disadvantaged individuals. One could even, very tentatively, in- fer that the gender-equitable effects could contribute to poverty alleviation and improved governance. But much more research needs to be done, and not all findings to date have been favorable. Although the aforementioned 2006-07 Asia Foundation study does not reach firm conclusions, the findings are generally positive. Both beneficiaries and opinion leaders indicate that NGOs that were the foci of the research were generally effective in conducting shalish and otherwise benefit their communities. 31 See http://www.villagecourts.org/index.php (accessed Sep. 29, 2012). 32 Akmeemana, supra note 6. 33 See, for example, Bangladesh Ministry of Women’s and Children’s Affairs (MOWCA), Back- ground Paper on Good Practices and Priorities to Combat Sexual Abuse and Exploitation of Children in Bangladesh (MOWCA 2001); T. Haque et al., In Search of Justice: Women’s Encounters with Alternative Dispute Resolution (Asia Foundation Apr. 2002); and United Nations Development Programme, Human Security in Bangladesh: In Search of Justice and Dignity (UNDP Sep. 2002). http://www.villagecourts.org/index.php The Political Economy of Improving Traditional Justice Systems 83 Yet, not all research on this matter has yielded positive results. Geirbo and Imam find that even though community members served by BRAC have become aware of dowry being illegal, they continue to pay it. Their research further indicates that deeply ingrained social practices and attitudes tend to persist—to some extent, even among some BRAC NGO workers, which has potentially powerful implications for their shalish-oriented work.34 A number of the Asia Foundation study’s focus groups report that illegal dowry and related problems continue despite the efforts of organizations to provide vari- ous kinds of community legal services, including shalish.35 Disputes, Crimes and Pathways of Redress provides provocative insights about how widespread Bangladeshis’ use of NGO justice services such as modified shalish is. Its findings indicate, inter alia, that far more people iden- tify Union Parishad chairpersons (operating informally, rather than in con- nection with formally convened village councils) as a first choice in seeking resolution of legal problems, compared to NGO shalish.36 As scrupulous as this study was, however, it raises as many questions as it answers about dispute resolution and redress. For example, due to the methodology employed by its survey research, the study identified relatively low rates of gender-specific problems (in a society in which dowry, under- age and multiple marriages, physical and psychological abuse of women, and women being cheated out of inheritances and other property are widespread). In addition, especially in view of the aforementioned research regarding the member-matbar-mulla triumvirate and related findings, there remains the is- sue of whether and to what extent people receive fair treatment from chair- persons (or to what extent that treatment is tainted by gender biases, graft, patronage, and other undue influences on their conduct). There also is the matter of whether the study’s design and peer review adequately involved NGO experts. Still, the study provides a useful basis for further research regarding not only NGOs’ and Union Parishad chairpersons’ services but also the public’s widespread lack of confidence in formal justice sector institutions.37 The Bank and the personnel involved in initiating and implementing this research should be commended for providing a model for digging deep into how people seek access to justice. Other Bangladesh-specific studies document NGO efficacy in other re- gards. One example is Hasle’s field research, which includes interviews with NU clients whose shalish agreements were arranged by NU-affiliated panels in 2002. NU’s follow-up records indicate that, of a sample of 37 selected by Hasle, 31 agreements were honored. In subsequently interviewing the clients, 34 Geirbo & Imam, supra note 12. 35 Asia Foundation, supra note 20. 36 Akmeemana, supra note 6. 37 Id. The World Bank Legal Review84 Hasle found that in all but one case the agreements were “more or less” hon- ored.38 Siddiqi’s research on both NU and ASK similarly document their strat- egies and efficacy.39 The findings of Hasle and Siddiqi are not inconsistent with that of Geirbo and Imam. Many of the disputes that Hasle scrutinized, for example, involved domestic violence that was reportedly halted through shalish interventions. In contrast, Geirbo and Imam researched dowry and related phenomena. The impact of modifying shalish might best be considered in the context of researching integrated legal services and/or development efforts that include but are not limited to improving how shalish operates. The Asia Foundation’s quantitative inquiries into legal services efficacy in Bangladesh, conducted un- der the auspices of a seven-country study of legal empowerment for the Asian Development Bank in 2000 –2001, found indications of poverty-alleviating and good-governance-promoting impact. More specifically, it compared control (that is, nonbeneficiary) populations with those belonging to either Banchte Shekha or Samata, an NGO that focuses on land advocacy, livelihood development, and access to government agricultural services.40 The findings indicate that the NGOs’ impact included restraining dowry; increasing successful citizen participation in joint actions and in influencing local government decisions; fostering positive community attitudes toward women’s rights and participation in governance; increasing use by the poor of government-managed lands that local elites otherwise seize; and dramatically reducing reliance on those elites for dispute resolution. The survey research found similar though more modest impact by MLAA in a number of these regards.41 The Foundation findings regarding dowry and other kinds of impact may not be totally consistent with the more qualitative inquiries of Geirbo and Imam. However, these two limited studies looked at different NGOs and communities. Expanded, rigorous research is called for. Implications for International Development Efforts to improve TJSs can be as much about social justice and governance as about dispute resolution. There is a tendency to view TJSs in terms of whether and how they settle disputes. The realities of shalish in Bangladesh contradict this view. Shalish in its traditional form often is a means of social control—of 38 Hasle, supra note 22. 39 D. M. Siddiqi, Paving the Way to Justice, supra note 18; Shalish and the Quest for Gender Justice, supra note 8; and Ain O Salish Kendra, supra note 27. 40 Stephen Golub & Kim McQuay, Legal Empowerment: Advancing Good Governance and Poverty Reduction, in Law and Policy Reform at the Asian Development Bank 135–49 (Asian Development Bank 2001). 41 Id. The Political Economy of Improving Traditional Justice Systems 85 men over women, of the relatively wealthy over the impoverished, and of religious and political leaders over their communities. Whether and to what extent these realities apply to traditional systems elsewhere is beyond the pur- view of this chapter. But the possibility that such systems manifest social con- trol—and the potential to advance social justice by modifying them—should not be overlooked. NGO engagement—and donor support for it—represents a potentially pro- ductive middle ground for efforts to improve TJSs. The experience of NGOs and their CBO partners in Bangladesh suggests that such organizations can productively work to keep the many advantages of TJSs while seeking to im- prove such systems. This effort represents a programmatic middle ground between simply leaving customary systems to their own devices and seek- ing to integrate them into the official state justice system. Pursuing this path does not preclude efforts to initiate or strengthen such integration. But given the fact that even after decades of existence, the state’s village court system remains largely moribund and in need of “activation” by a UNDP project, and given the degree to which that system likely lends itself to political influence and traditional attitudes, NGO engagement with shalish arguably compares favorably with reliance on that system. This is particularly salient in terms of improving dispute resolution and for the aforementioned considerations regarding social justice. It most likely makes sense to support similar civil society efforts elsewhere. However, the reality remains that many beneficiaries of NGO modifica- tion of TJSs may go from “worse to bad.” For example, a farmer may recoup only a portion of the crop proceeds rightly due him, but this is better than nothing. An impoverished woman who in a society that offers more economic opportunities might be able to escape a dysfunctional marriage may opt to re- turn to it by dint of NGO efforts. But this may be preferable to her alternatives outside the marriage: destitution, ostracization, homelessness, or malnourish- ment for herself or her children. On a more hopeful note, it should be borne in mind that community dy- namics in Bangladesh and elsewhere are not stagnant. The 2011 study on NU reached encouraging conclusions about the progress that the NGO and other women’s empowerment strategies are making.42 This author’s observation of NGO-modified shalish in the 1990s found a markedly higher level of engage- ment by women over the years. The possibility of litigation can be a powerful incentive for reaching and hon- oring a TJS agreement. The threat or fear of being taken to court by lawyers associated with an NGO can make an otherwise recalcitrant party cooperate with shalish. Especially when the judiciary is backlogged, corrupt, and oth- erwise dysfunctional, the expense of litigation and uncertainty of result can persuade a party to avoid becoming enmeshed in the formal wheels of justice. 42 Higgitt, supra note 23. The World Bank Legal Review86 Ironically, then, some NGO engagement with shalish implicitly weaves together the country’s nonstate and state legal systems. NGOs sometimes take cases straight to court if criminal or otherwise severe violations of a client’s rights are at play. More commonly, though, NGO engagement integrates the two systems by holding out the possibility of turning to the judiciary should shalish fail. On the other hand, under some circumstances, the possibility of going to court may not appeal to the NGO client or may not intimidate his or her op- ponent. Power imbalances are salient in this regard. An influential person may have resources to afford representation or significant sway in the community, making the client reluctant to go the judicial route. Are NGOs’ potential dual roles in shalish inappropriate? In many instances of shalish, NGOs do not take sides—their influence is on the process as a whole, rather than individual disputes. They convene and moderate in a neu- tral manner, rather than advocating and litigating in a partisan one. Still, the very fact that some convene sessions in response to one party’s request can make her/him a kind of client. And, as discussed above, when they raise the possibility of taking recalcitrant parties to court (and occasionally actually do so), they take a clear stand in their clients’ favor. Are these dual roles—neu- tral convener and partisan advocate—inappropriate? This raises issues of un- checked, unaccountable NGO influence. The issue may be less problematic than it seems, however. There certainly is a tension between the two roles. And there is room for abuse by NGO per- sonnel. But the balance in many disputes is typically tipped against women and other disadvantaged persons to begin with. There is no assurance that the police or courts redress power imbalances any better than NGOs do; in fact, there are indications to the contrary. Even if NGOs do not always act with ab- solute integrity or clarity in deciding whom they will support, their net impact is to make for fairer processes that can sometimes advance social justice. One mechanism for advancing NGO accountability could be the intro- duction or strengthening of systems by which the organization’s management obtains community feedback on whether and how its local personnel are act- ing responsibly. Although there are examples of such mechanisms in other countries—the dispute-resolution NGO Timap in Sierra Leone, for example— it is beyond the purview of this chapter to explore whether and to what extent similar approaches exist in Bangladesh. NGO authority lends weight to shalish. The credibility and influence of an NGO can encourage the parties to participate in shalish and to abide by the results. This influence can flow, for example, from an NGO generating donor resources or otherwise bringing benefits to a community that grants the or- ganization a measure of power. Or the NGO may be based in Dhaka or have influential government, donor, or civil society connections there, which sug- gests to many on a local level that it is a sophisticated, well-connected outfit. The Political Economy of Improving Traditional Justice Systems 87 The NGO can act as a countervailing influence to the corruption or politiciza- tion that may otherwise affect dispute resolution. Yet, the degree of this influence is limited in many areas. Local officials’ and party activists’ political power also generates resources, sometimes far beyond those of an NGO. In addition, they may have criminal or police links that allow them to bring force to bear or otherwise act with impunity. And certainly, not all influential persons in a community necessarily view NGO generation of resources or contacts as unmitigated goods. To the extent that NGOs do have considerable local influence, this has implications for the trade-off between approaches that prioritize their direct engagement with organizing shalish and those that concentrate on building up CBOs that can act independently. An argument for the former is that such engagement is necessary in most of Bangladesh for the foreseeable future, be- cause change is a slow process and countervailing, conservative social dynam- ics are too strong for CBOs to counter. The case for the latter approach is that it is ultimately more sustainable and that the NGO remains in the picture to pro- vide advice, training, legal assistance, and other support on an ongoing basis. The involvement of influential persons can be crucial for shalish. Influential persons on the NGO-modified shalish panels may combine with community mores to create pressure for both parties to reach and honor an agreement. In some cases, long-term NGO engagement in a community on a number of fronts may make such persons’ involvement less important. With its years of involvement with literacy, livelihoods, organizing, and other activities ben- efiting women, Banchte Shekha is a case in point. In some instances, however, NGOs may need to compromise with and try to co-opt influential figures, even if they tend to be conservative in their outlooks, rather than attempt to exclude them from shalish. Nevertheless, there is a line to walk in such efforts. NGOs are effective to the extent that they mitigate traditional shalishdars’ gender biases and other undue influences. The NGOs do this by helping women join the shalish panels and otherwise participate in the process. They also seek to involve commu- nity leaders and educated persons—teachers, for example—who may have broader perspectives. The integration of TJS modification with broader socioeconomic development work holds promise for affecting underlying community dynamics. Shalish is a product of underlying community dynamics. To the extent that improving shalish hinges on affecting those dynamics, it is important to see NGO engage- ment with shalish as part of an integrated approach to poverty alleviation, improved governance, and social change. This is not to discount the value of straightforward income generation, microfinance, and other operations. But attacking problems such as government corruption and gender inequity requires a long-term, multipronged approach. This view might seem to weigh in favor of simply supporting socioeco- nomic development NGOs for service delivery, with legal services NGOs The World Bank Legal Review88 playing supportive (though still crucial) back-up roles. But there are a few reasons to avoid drawing such a stark conclusion. First, insufficient data are available to support it. It would take years of rigorous research to make that judgment. Second, because legal-services NGOs are sophisticated in their le- gal knowledge and activities, they bring countervailing strengths to the table. Finally, and perhaps most significant, in many situations in Bangladesh the two kinds of NGOs are already cooperating in ways (such as training and other support by the legal services groups to the socioeconomic development ones) that produce integrated approaches. A cautious approach to strengthening village courts and other government dispute resolution mechanisms is advisable. MLAA’s interest in fortifying the village court system deserves respect, given its trailblazing role in community legal services in Bangladesh. UNDP’s initiative to work with these bodies also could bear fruit. Nevertheless, it is best to proceed cautiously with govern- ment-centered work in Bangladesh and other countries. NGO-assisted shalish merits a greater investment of donor resources. There are several reasons for such caution regarding village courts. First, the often corrupt and increasingly politicized nature of even the most basic local government functions, together with criminal links to politics, means that the village courts could be similarly infected. Conversely, there is also the more mundane constraint that Union Parishad chairpersons are often too busy to invest time and effort in participating in the process. Third, the prob- lematic history of efforts to energize the system should be taken into account. In addition, MLAA aside, not all NGOs see the village courts as a vehicle for sound dispute resolution. NGO-assisted shalish merits a greater investment of resources because, when integrated with socioeconomic development efforts, it has the poten- tial to modify underlying community dynamics in ways that reach beyond dispute resolution. The village courts could perpetuate such underlying dynamics to the disadvantage of women and the poor. In a related vein, al- though Disputes, Crimes and Pathways of Redress indicates that Union Parishad chairpersons play important dispute-resolution roles even outside the village courts structure, they may also perpetuate unjust community dynamics. 89 Intellectual Property Facilitating Technology Transfer for Development Roy F. WaldRon In 1994, the Agreement on Trade-Related Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights (TRIPS) established minimum standards for the regulation of many forms of intellectual property (IP), including the right of patent owners to pre- vent unauthorized persons from using a patented process and making, us- ing, offering for sale, selling, or importing a patented product or a product obtained directly by the patented process.1 All members of the World Trade Organization (WTO) were required to adopt TRIPS-compliant IP laws, with the exception of least-developed countries (LDCs), which have until 2016 to apply TRIPS provisions for pharmaceutical patents.2 The most comprehensive and influential international treaty on intellectual property rights, TRIPS is the global baseline for IP protection. To successfully attract imported technology and to build the necessary preconditions for adapting the imported technology, developing countries needed a supportive environment that would facilitate such transfers, which included strong intellectual property protection and enforcement. To a large extent, this was the rationale behind the negotiation of TRIPS: technology would flow to those developing countries that adopted strong intellectual property protection and enforcement. Developing countries view technology transfer as part of the bargain in which they agreed to protect intellectual property rights. TRIPS was crafted to create a common understanding of intellectual property rights globally and to provide its signatories (trading partners) with protections and certainties to ensure fair competition through a regime of IP rights. Articles 7 and 66.2 promote the practice of technology transfer, with the goal of ensuring that The author wishes to thank Sharon Reiche and Angela Wasunna, both of Pfizer, for their contributions in the preparation of this chapter. The views expressed are those of the author and do not reflect the policy or position of Pfizer Inc. 1 Agreement on Trade-Related Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights (Apr. 15, 1994), Mar- rakesh Agreement Establishing the World Trade Organization, Annex 1C, The Legal Texts: The Results of the Uruguay Round of Multilateral Trade Negotiations 320 (1999), 1869 U.N.T.S. 299, 33 I.L.M. 1197 (1994), article 28 (hereinafter, TRIPS). 2 See World Trade Organization. Declaration on the TRIPS Agreement and Public Health, WT/ MIN(01)/DEC/2 (Nov. 20, 2001). The World Bank Legal Review90 technology holders are assured a favorable environment for investing in de- veloping countries—and transferring their technology.3 The objectives section of Article 7 states that the “protection and enforce- ment of intellectual property rights should contribute to the promotion of technological innovation and to the transfer and dissemination of technol- ogy, to the mutual advantage of producers and users of technological knowledge and in a manner conducive to social and economic welfare, and to a balance of rights and obligations.”4 The obligation for developed countries to provide incentives to enterprises and institutions to promote and encourage technol- ogy transfer to LDC members is found in Article 66.2.5 To ensure compliance, developed countries are required to submit reports on actions they have taken or plan to take in order to fulfill their commitments under this article.6 Despite the reference to technology transfer in Articles 7 and 66.2, TRIPS does not set out a universally recognized definition of technology transfer— leaving it open to legal and policy interpretation. There are many ways to transfer technology. Foreign direct investment, trade, and mobility of human resources are important sources of technology transfer and knowledge spill- overs. Imports and exports, scientific collaborations, knowledge-sharing ven- tures, and capacity building help disseminate technology information from one source to another.7 Proprietary knowledge may be revealed during licens- ing agreements and joint ventures with local partners, thus giving rise to the transfer of technology.8 Additionally, foreign direct investment, a significant indicator of economic development and attractiveness of an economy, leads to technology transfer when multinational enterprises transfer information to their subsidiaries, some of which has the potential to “leak” into the host econ- omy. The host country benefits via the experts, skills, and financial resources that are required to develop and make use of technology, as well as the de- velopment of human resources, higher wages, and improvement in corporate governance standards.9 3 TRIPS, supra note 1, Articles 7 and 66.2. 4 Id., at Article 7 (emphasis added). 5 Id., at Article 66.2 (“Developed country Members shall provide incentives to enterprises and institutions in their territories for the purpose of promoting and encouraging technology transfer to least-developed country Members in order to enable them to create a sound and viable technological base”). 6 See World Trade Organization, Implementation of Article 66.2 of the TRIPS Agreement IP/C/28 (Feb. 20, 2003). 7 See Bernard Hoekman, Keith Maskus, & Kamal Saggi, Transfer of Technology to Developing Countries: Unilateral and Multilateral Policy Options, Institute of Behavioral Science, Research Program on Political and Economic Change, University of Colorado at Boulder Working Paper PEC2004-0003 (May 2004). 8 See Thomas Müller & Monika Schnitzer, Technology Transfer and Spillovers in International Joint Ventures, 68 J. Intl. Eco. 456–68 (2006). 9 See Maria Maher, Hans Christiansen, & Fabienne Fortanier, Growth, Technology Transfer and Foreign Direct Investment (OECD 2011) (prepared for the OECD Global Forum on Interna- tional Investment: New Horizons and Policy Challenges for Foreign Direct Investment in the Intellectual Property 91 During the 37th Session of the Working Group on Trade and Transfer of Technology (WGTTT),10 Francis Gurry, the director general of the World Intel- lectual Property Organization (WIPO), discussed his organization’s work on innovation and technology transfer. During his presentation, Gurry quoted Sir Francis Bacon’s dictum that “knowledge is power,” extrapolating to pro- pose that the sharing of “technological superiority” is a transfer of power.11 He considered what is required to entice companies to “do away with their competitive power” through technology transfer; in his view, the existence of suitable market conditions and market possibilities in the host country are vital for the transfer of technology to occur.12 The Role of Pharmaceutical Intellectual Property and Technology Transfer in Developing Countries Protection of Intellectual Property Is Critical As Gurry implied, the private sector considers a variety of factors when decid- ing whether to engage in technology transfer. To create the necessary condi- tions to foster confidence to invest in and export new technologies, as well as to develop new technologies in collaboration with developing countries, there must be strong IP protection and effective enforcement in those countries. As an intellectual property–dependent industry, the pharmaceutical industry did not initially engage in technology transfer in developing countries where IP protection was lacking. With TRIPS, a framework was created that encour- ages the rapid dissemination of ideas and efficient technology transfer, both of which are critical for technology-intensive, high-risk sectors. The pharmaceutical industry’s willingness to invest in critical value-added production and research and development (R&D) facilities in developing countries is directly linked to the strength and effectiveness of their IP systems. By safeguarding property against unauthorized commercial exploitation, effective IP protection provides predictability and, more important, the ability for a company to enter into license agreements and contracts. Because patents provide a legal basis for revealing proprietary information to subsidiaries and licensees, companies are less inclined to engage in technology transactions 21st Century, Mexico City, Nov. 26–27, 2001). 10 In 2001, during the WTO’s Ministerial Conference in Doha, Qatar, a number of developing countries proposed the establishment of a working group under the umbrella of the WTO General Council to study the relationship between international trade and technology trans- fer and to make recommendations on ways to increase the flow of technology to developing countries. The proposal was accepted, and the Working Group on Trade and Transfer of Technology (WGTTT) was established. See World Trade Organization, Ministerial Declara- tion WT/MIN(01)/DEC/1 (Nov. 20, 2001), article 37. 11 World Trade Organization, Working Group on Trade and Transfer of Technology. 37th Ses- sion, Notes on the Meeting of Nov. 3, 2011, WT/WGTTT/M/37 ( Jan. 13, 2012). 12 Id. The World Bank Legal Review92 without effective IP protection.13 IP protection helps pharmaceutical compa- nies justify investments in the inherently risky, costly, complex, and lengthy R&D and regulatory process, and ensure long-term foreign investor commit- ment to the local market. Technology transfers that follow in the wake of strong IP protection also help curtail “brain drain” by generating a more qualified and technically ad- vanced labor force that will be motivated to remain in their home countries. Brain drain is “the departure of educated or professional people from one country, economic sector, or field for another usually for better pay or living conditions.”14 When these skilled workers leave their home country in search of better opportunities in wealthier countries, the developing country fails to benefit from its considerable investment of public funds to educate the person who now brings his or her skills to the developed world.15 The loss of these workers negatively affects the developing country’s ability to absorb tech- nology transfer, because knowledge of scientific and technical information is necessary to accomplish technology transfer and advance development.16 By providing companies with increased incentives—such as a supportive IP en- vironment—to establish R&D facilities in developing countries, countries may entice local individuals to return or remain in country to capitalize on these opportunities. IP plays an essential role in technological development and dissemination and provides incentives for innovation in developing countries. Developing countries have the potential to attract not only the transfer of existing technol- ogy but also the transfer of new technologies through stronger patent rights.17 Although the degree to which a country benefits from IP depends on the coun- try’s relative strengths and socioeconomic characteristics, in countries with strong and effective IP regimes in place, there is a significant link between increased incentives for local innovation and the transfer of technologies that encourage local innovation and economic growth.18 By providing the right in- centives and removing barriers to the timely launch of innovative medicines, the patients and the private sector benefit. 13 See Hoekman, Maskus, & Saggi, supra note 7. 14 Merriam-Webster Dictionary, available at http://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary. 15 See John Barton, New Trends in Technology Transfer: Implications for National and International Policy, International Centre for Trade and Sustainable Development Issue Paper No. 18 (Feb. 2007). 16 See Keith Maskus & Jerome Reichman ed., International Public Goods and Transfer of Technology under a Globalized Intellectual Property Regime 57 (Cambridge U. Press 2005). 17 See Walter G. Park & Douglas C. Lippoldt, Technology Transfer and the Economic Implications of the Strengthening of Intellectual Property Rights in Developing Countries, OECD Trade Policy Working Paper No. 62, 25 (2008). 18 Id., at 28. http://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary Intellectual Property 93 Other Factors Conducive to Technology Transfer Strong and effective IP protection and enforcement, generally a prerequisite for any out-licensing or joint-venture decision, is only one of many factors in- fluencing a company’s decision to engage in technology transfer. Factors such as predictable regulatory standards, government commitment to education, a stable business environment, and alignment with the government’s economic development priorities play an essential role. A reliable and predictable registration process for pharmaceutical prod- ucts is important in providing motivations and incentives to engage in tech- nology transfer.19 A heavily regulated sector, the pharmaceutical industry must meet rigorous standards involving safety, quality, and efficacy in order to ensure the welfare of patients. Therefore, when relying on local production, companies frequently transfer their technology to entities based in part on their capacity to meet international quality standards. This in turn contributes to the development of the local pharmaceutical industry. The presence of a highly skilled workforce is vital to the development, application, utilization, and integration of new technology20 and makes the investment climate more attractive for foreign investors. Due to their depth of knowledge, these highly trained and educated workers are essential for technology transfer to occur. Through improvements in education and in the operating environment, developing countries are encouraged to promote the knowledge, experience, and skills necessary to enable workers to bring eco- nomic value and a competitive advantage to technical companies. These com- panies, in turn, provide education and training and may bring new informa- tion, skills, and technology to host nations. A country’s relative political, economic, and social stability will influence a company’s decision whether to transfer technology and is often considered a precondition for technology transfer to occur.21 Long periods of stability lead to stronger and more successful partnerships because stability lowers the risk of doing business in an unfamiliar environment and provides companies with increased confidence to implement long-term business strategies and assur- ance that their goals will be sustainable. Economic reforms and other efforts that promote trade, investment, nondiscriminatory policies, legal frameworks, and national infrastructure add to the attractiveness of a country with regard to technology transfer.22 As governments begin to understand the interrela- tionship between health care and economic outcomes, investment in health care systems and infrastructures will become a high priority.23 19 See Technology Transfer: A Collaborative Approach to Improve Global Health (IFPMA 2011). 20 See Barton, supra note 15. 21 See Technology Transfer, supra note 19. 22 See Maher, Christiansen, & Fortanier, supra note 9. 23 See Technology Transfer, supra note 19. The World Bank Legal Review94 By aligning themselves with a system that promotes technology trans- fer, developing countries are more likely to create medicines and technolo- gies that address their public health needs and enable local and regional solutions.24 Technology transfer arrangements can create strong alliances and collaborations that can be leveraged for long-term commercial and economic advantage. A supportive environment that encourages these transactions is a win-win situation for both the private sector and the developing country. The R&D activities of companies can enhance economic and social progress in developing countries. In turn, the development of a robust and dynamic inno- vation system in a developing country will expand commercial opportunities for companies. Examples of Technology Transfer in the Pharmaceutical Industry A goal of technology transfer, in the context of pharmaceuticals, is to promote access to new medicines and technologies for diseases that affect a local popu- lation. Access to medicines in developing countries is a high-priority issue in the global health sector, including for multinational pharmaceutical compa- nies.25 Technology transfer can directly affect research for neglected tropical diseases (NTDs) that primarily occur in developing countries. Many forms of collaboration and alliances have been developed to promote research and treatment of these diseases, and many include a technology transfer element.26 These types of arrangements, which are becoming more frequent, demon- strate that solutions to societal issues can be found through partnerships and the sharing of knowledge without undermining IP rights. Pfizer’s Research Partnership with Drugs for Neglected Diseases Initiative According to the World Health Organization (WHO), NTDs affect more than 1 billion people each year and are endemic in 149 countries.27 For NTDs such as leishmaniasis and human African trypanosomiasis (HAT), infections oc- cur among the poorest people in rural areas. To accelerate the elimination or 24 See Luis A. Salicrup & Lenka Fedorková, Challenges and Opportunities for Enhancing Biotech- nology and Technology Transfer in Developing Countries, 24 Biotech. Advances 69–79 (2006). 25 See Sofia Gruskin & Zyde Raad, Are Drug Companies Living Up to Their Human Rights Respon- sibilities? Moving toward Assessment (Harvard School of Public Health 2010); Carsten Fink, Intellectual Property and Public Health: An Overview of the Debate with a Focus on US Policy (World Bank Development Research Group 2008); Joyce Meng, Expanding Global Access: A Comparative Analysis of Pharmaceutical Corporate Social Responsibility Initiative (unpub- lished paper 2007); and Greg Martin et al., Balancing Intellectual Monopoly Privileges and the Need for Essential Medicines, 3(4) Globalization and Health (2007). 26 James T. Gathii, Approaches to Accessing Essential Medicines and the TRIPS Agreement, 15(2) Harv. J. L. & Tech. (2002). 27 See the WHO-sponsored Global Health Observatory website’s section Neglected Tropical Diseases, http://www.who.int.gho/ (accessed Apr. 2012); and World Health Organization, Accelerating Work to Overcome the Global Impact of Neglected Tropical Diseases: A Roadmap for Implementation (WHO 2012). http://www.who.int.gho/ Intellectual Property 95 control of these diseases, Pfizer entered into an agreement with Drugs for Ne- glected Diseases initiative (DNDi) in 2009, in which Pfizer agreed to provide DNDi with access to a Pfizer library of proprietary compounds to screen for new potential targets against leishmaniasis, Chagas disease, and HAT.28 This arrangement, which partners Pfizer’s research infrastructure with DNDi’s neglected disease expertise, maximizes the chances of identifying promis- ing starting points for drug discovery programs. Although Pfizer owns the IP on these compounds, any novel leads are a candidate for licensing agree- ments with regard to NTDs. The Pfizer-DNDi partnership demonstrates that the burden of finding solutions to diseases endemic to developing countries does not rest with a single entity. Through the transfer of technology, dupli- cation of research and repetitiveness of efforts are minimized, resulting in a more streamlined and focused approach that draws on the complementary strengths of each organization. The collaboration has identified promising leads, and DNDi will continue research, development, and commercialization based on these leads. GlaxoSmithKline’s Vaccine Development Initiative with the Oswaldo Cruz Foundation In 2009, GlaxoSmithKline (GSK) announced a partnership with the Oswaldo Cruz Foundation (Fiocruz) to develop and manufacture vaccines for public health needs in Brazil.29 The agreement created an R&D collaboration pro- gram at Fiocruz to develop a vaccine for dengue fever, a mosquito-borne viral infection that is the leading cause of serious illness and death among children in Asian and Latin American countries and for which no specific treatment is available.30 With approximately half of the world’s population at risk of contracting dengue fever,31 this joint R&D initiative will enhance Bra- zilian capacity to improve the health of patients by protecting them against this disease. GSK also partnered with Fiocruz in 2009 to provide access to the tech- nology behind GSK’s 10-valent conjugate vaccine for pediatric pneumococ- cal disease, or Synflorix.32 Under the agreement, GSK supplied Fiocruz with Synflorix until the technology transfer was complete; the vaccine has since been incorporated into Brazil’s national immunization program.33 In shar- ing knowledge and technology between the two organizations, scientists from GSK and Fiocruz work across facilities in Brazil and Belgium to protect 28 See Pfizer and DNDi Advancing International Research Efforts in the Fight against Neglected Tropi- cal Diseases, DNDi Press Release (Nov. 18, 2009). 29 See GSK and Brazil’s Fiocruz Form Partnership for New R&D Effort and Increased Vaccine Access, GSK Press Release (Aug. 17, 2009). 30 Id.; World Health Organization, Dengue and Severe Dengue, Fact Sheet No. 117 ( Jan. 2012). 31 Id. 32 See GSK and Brazil’s Fiocruz, supra note 29. 33 Id. The World Bank Legal Review96 children from diseases such as pneumonia, meningitis, and bacteremia.34 The two organizations extended their partnership in 2010, enabling scientists at Fiocruz and GSK’s Tres Cantos facility in Spain to share new ideas, know-how, and research on diseases such as malaria, tuberculosis, Chagas disease, and leishmaniasis.35 In collaborations such as these, the transfer of technology and expertise drives discovery and development efforts to produce new and innovative medicines to treat diseases that affect people in developing countries. Antonio de Pádua Risolia Barbosa, deputy director of production at the Immunobio- logical Technology Institute, or Bio-Manguinhos unit, of Fiocruz, states, “Be- sides our own innovation and development, we have partnerships with local and global organizations, and we use technology transfer to accelerate the viability of the products for the population.”36 WIPO Re:Search—Sharing Innovation in the Fight against NTDs Recognizing the need for progress in neglected disease research and under- standing that such research is the collective responsibility of the entire global health community, WIPO Re:Search was formed in 2011 through the efforts of several of the world’s leading pharmaceutical companies, WIPO, and BIO Ventures for Global Health (BVGH).37 WIPO Re:Search provides three services: • A comprehensive platform/database, hosted by WIPO, of patent and oth- er proprietary information (for example, clinical trial results, regulatory status) on compounds and technologies available for licensing for NTD research • A partnership hub, managed by BVGH, providing a forum where inter- ested parties can learn about available licensing opportunities, available funding for research, and networking opportunities in their research fields • A range of specific supporting activities, such as facilitating licensing agreements and dispute resolution38 WIPO Re:Search aims to promote the transfer of knowledge through the facilitation of nontraditional partnerships and by encouraging organiza- tions to share proprietary information publicly. WIPO Re:Search also offers researchers in developing countries access to research facilities and scientists 34 Id. 35 See GlaxoSmithKline and Fiocruz Extend Innovative Collaboration to Research and Develop New Medicines for Neglected Tropical Diseases, GSK Press Release (Nov. 12, 2010). 36 Patricia Van Arnum, Technology Transfer in Global Health Initiatives, 7(4) Pharmaceutical Tech- nology Sourcing and Management (Apr. 6, 2011). 37 See Leading Pharmaceutical Companies & Research Institutions Offer IP and Expertise for Use in Treating Neglected Tropical Diseases as Part of WIPO Re:Search, WIPO Press Release (Oct. 26, 2011). 38 See WIPO Re:Search website, www.wiporesearch.org (accessed Mar. 2012). www.wiporesearch.org Intellectual Property 97 working in leading pharmaceutical companies and laboratories, an important step in the technology transfer process. The structure of the consortium dem- onstrates that solutions to societal issues can be solved through partnerships without undermining IP. Users of WIPO Re:Search are granted royalty-free licenses to IP for re- search and development, anywhere in the world, of products and technolo- gies or services for the sole purpose of addressing public health needs for NTDs in LDCs. Users are also granted royalty-free licenses to make or have made such products, technologies, or services. These licenses also allow users to sell these products in LDCs royalty-free. Users are allowed to retain owner- ship of and apply for registration of IP as they deem fit, but are encouraged to license through WIPO Re:Search new IP rights generated under an agreement made pursuant to membership in the consortium.39 WIPO Re:Search leverages expertise to develop new products and tech- nologies, improves research productivity, allows the monetization of technol- ogies and IP assets that would otherwise go unused in the organization’s own business, and makes more efficient use of research investments by enhanc- ing the exchange of mutually beneficial knowledge. Through information- sharing consortiums such as WIPO Re:Search, products and technologies can be brought to market faster and more efficiently. The consortium has received the commitment of more than 50 private and public organizations dedicated to accelerating R&D for NTDs, malaria, and tuberculosis, including Pfizer, GlaxoSmithKline, AstraZeneca, DNDi, Fiocruz, Medicines for Malaria Ventures (MMV), PATH, and the Walter Reed Army Institute of Research (WRAIR).40 Although the commitment and willingness of these partners to transfer technology through WIPO Re:Search is a step toward addressing the R&D challenges that affect the developing world, sus- tained elimination of these diseases is possible only with a commitment by individual countries to ensure access to safe water, proper waste disposal and treatment, basic sanitation, and improved living conditions.41 ViiV Healthcare—Joint Venture between Pfizer and GSK According to the Joint United Nations Programme on HIV/AIDS (UNAIDS), the growth of the global AIDS epidemic appears to have stabilized, and the annual number of new HIV infections has been steadily declining.42 However, approximately 34 million people worldwide continue to live with HIV,43 and 39 See WIPO Re:Search: Sharing Innovation in the Fight against Neglected Tropical Diseases, Guiding Principles (May 2011), available at http://www.wiporesearch.org. 40 Id. 41 See World Health Organization, Accelerating Work to Overcome the Global Impact of Neglected Tropical Diseases, supra note 27. 42 See UNAIDS, Report on the Global AIDS Epidemic 16 (UNAIDS 2010). 43 See UNAIDS website, http://www.unaids.org (accessed Mar. 2012). http://www.wiporesearch.org http://www.unaids.org The World Bank Legal Review98 more than 7,000 people are newly infected every day.44 Discrimination and stigmatization remain, and many people continue to lack access to the antiret- roviral (ARV) medicines and health care support they require; only one-third of the 15 million people living with HIV in low- and middle-income countries who need treatment are receiving it.45 To further efforts to deliver advances in treatment and care for people liv- ing with HIV, Pfizer and GSK created a joint venture and established a new specialist HIV company, ViiV Healthcare, in 2009.46 ViiV Healthcare is focused solely on the research, development, and commercialization of HIV medicines and has a single, sustainable, not-for-profit price for each ARV that it makes available to a wide range of patients in LDCs and sub-Saharan Africa—a total of 69 countries, representing 80% of all people living with HIV/AIDS world- wide.47 ViiV Healthcare extends royalty-free voluntary licensing of its innova- tive drugs to generic manufacturers producing and distributing therapies to people living with HIV in LDCs, low-income countries, and all of sub-Saharan Africa. As of 2012, ViiV Healthcare had granted 11 voluntary licenses for its ARVs.48 By combining the research efforts and knowledge of Pfizer and GSK, ViiV Healthcare will achieve more for those whose lives are affected by HIV than ei- ther company could have achieved alone. Various ViiV initiatives, such as the ViiV Healthcare Effect, strive to strengthen education, support services, local health care capacity, and capabilities through education and collaboration.49 Pfizer’s Global Health Fellows Since 2003, more than 300 Pfizer colleagues have participated in the Global Health Fellows Program, an international corporate volunteer program that places Pfizer colleagues in short-term assignments with international devel- opment organizations in emerging markets.50 The objective of the program is to strengthen the ability of health care providers in these countries to care for their patients. Through Pfizer’s partnership with more than 40 organizations, colleagues are provided the opportunity to transfer their professional medical and business expertise to optimize local supply chains and business functions 44 See UNAIDS, 2011–2015 Strategy: Getting to Zero (UNAIDS 2010). 45 See UNAIDS, supra note 42, at 7. 46 See ViiV Healthcare Launches: A New Specialist HIV Company Dedicated to Delivering Advances in HIV Treatment and Care, ViiV press release (Nov. 3, 2009). 47 See ViiV Healthcare website, www.viivhealthcare.com (accessed Mar. 2012). 48 Id. 49 The ViiV Healthcare Effect is a portal that introduces the company’s approach to partner- ships and showcases best practices throughout the world. It provides users the opportunity to hear directly from people creating new solutions on the ground and to learn what has worked and how those efforts can be applied or expanded to support more communities. See ViiV Healthcare Effect website, www.viivhealthcareeffect.com (accessed Mar. 2012). 50 See Pfizer website, Global Health Fellows, available at http://www.pfizer.com/ghf (ac- cessed Mar. 2012). www.viivhealthcare.com www.viivhealthcareeffect.com http://www.pfizer.com/ghf Intellectual Property 99 and improve health prevention approaches. This program demonstrates that technology transfer encompasses expertise and technical skills. WHO’s TDR Career Development Fellowship Program In 1975, the Special Programme for Research and Training in Tropical Diseases (TDR), sponsored by the United Nations Children’s Fund (UNICEF), the United Nations Development Programme (UNDP), the World Bank, and WHO, was established as a scientific collaboration to coordinate, support, and influence global efforts to combat diseases affecting disadvantaged populations.51 TDR founded the Career Development Fellowship on Clinical Research & Development in 2009 with the support of the Bill & Melinda Gates Founda- tion. Researchers and public health professionals from disease-endemic coun- tries are awarded a 12-month training opportunity with pharmaceutical com- panies in order to receive specialized in-house training to acquire experience in clinical trial management, R&D project management, regulatory compli- ance, and good practices.52 By focusing on human resources development and capacity building, individual fellows are able to maintain their existing capa- bilities, strengthen their potential, and obtain new skills that are not normally taught in academic centers. Once the fellowship has been completed and the fellows return to their home countries, they have the opportunity to assume a leading role in the global effort on R&D, thereby enhancing the develop- ing country’s capacity for product development. In 2009, Pfizer hosted two developing-world clinical researchers as part of the TDR program.53 In 2011, Eisai, a major Japan-based pharmaceutical company, welcomed a TDR clinical research fellow whose goal is to build the health care capacity of developing countries; Eisai provides the fellow with the opportunity to learn about drug development from the US and Japanese perspective.54 Upon completion of the fellowship, the fellow returned to his home country, Colombia, to develop and arrange local and regional academic meetings to educate his counterparts in the study of tropical and neglected diseases.55 Looking toward the Future: Navigating an Evolving Landscape The world today is quite different than it was a few decades ago; trade, as well as scientific and education research systems, is highly globalized, and an 51 See World Health Organization website, TDR, available at http://www.who.int/tdr (ac- cessed Mar. 2012). 52 See International Federation of Pharmaceutical Manufacturers & Associations (IFPMA) web- site, Capacity Building, http://www.ifpma.org/global-health/access/capacity-building .html (accessed Mar. 2012). 53 See Pfizer Corporate Responsibility Report (2009), available at http://www.pfizer.com/respon sibility (accessed Mar. 2012). 54 See Eisai Takes Second Clinical Research Fellow from Developing World, available at http://www .eisai.com (accessed Mar. 2012). 55 Id. http://www.who.int/tdr http://www.ifpma.org/global-health/access/capacity-building.html http://www.ifpma.org/global-health/access/capacity-building.html http://www.pfizer.com/responsibility http://www.eisai.com http://www.eisai.com http://www.pfizer.com/responsibility The World Bank Legal Review100 increasing number of developing countries are becoming more technologi- cally sophisticated. According to the World Bank’s Global Economic Prospects report, however, “the world economy has entered a very difficult phase characterized by significant downside risks and fragility,” with developing- country growth expected to decline to 5.4 percent and 6.0 percent versus 6.2 percent and 6.3 percent in June 2011 projections.56 Developing countries should be encouraged to identify new drivers of growth, one of which is technology transfer. Although technology transfer can be a time-consuming and complex process, given the right incentives and strong interest by developing countries in increasing their access to international technologies, companies from developed countries can assist LDCs in achiev- ing sustained economic change and growth in domestic productivity. Intel- lectual property, in particular, helps realize the model necessary to transfer technology and should be viewed as a vital tool that can aid in social and eco- nomic progress. As countries develop their own assets, they will have greater incentives to respect the IP framework and implement and enforce strong IP regimes that will aid in the facilitation of new types of positive partnerships. Although not all countries are equally prepared to integrate complex tech- nology into their production chains, the level of complexity on the technology transfer spectrum varies, beginning with knowledge and skills training as the most basic form. Therefore, the transfer of technology should be encouraged in all regions of the developing world, because building local capacity can play a major role in moving LDCs to the next stage of development and sig- nificantly affect the pace of innovation within these countries. 56 World Bank, Global Economic Prospects: Uncertainties and Vulnerabilities ( Jan. 2012). 101 Transforming through Transparency Opening Up the World Bank’s Sanctions Regime Conrad C. daly and Frank a. Fariello, Jr. The World Bank,1 whose mission it is to fight against global poverty,2 is one of the world’s premier international financial institutions.3 The Bank’s sanctions system emerges out of the Bank’s fiduciary obligation to ensure that the funds that its shareholders contribute are used with attention to economy and effi- ciency for their intended purposes.4 As fraud and corruption compromise the effectiveness of development projects5 and have a perverse and deleterious 1 In this chapter, “World Bank” is used to refer collectively to two institutions, the Interna- tional Bank for Reconstruction and Development (IBRD) and the International Development Association (IDA). IBRD began operations in 1947, with the purpose of providing loans to developing countries, while IDA was founded in 1960 to provide financing on concession- al terms to the poorest and least credit-worthy developing countries. The World Bank is part of the World Bank Group, a constellation of institutions including, in addition to IBRD and IDA, the International Finance Corporation (IFC), the Multilateral Investment Guar- antee Agency (MIGA), and the International Center for Settlement of Investment Disputes (ICSID). 2 See IBRD Articles of Agreement, Article I, Section i (Dec. 27, 1945) (“To assist in the recon- struction and development of territories of members”); and IDA Articles of Agreement, Ar- ticle I (“The purposes of the Association are to promote economic development, increase productivity and thus raise standards of living in the less-developed areas of the world in- cluded within the Association’s membership”). The first president of the World Bank, Eu- gene Meyer, highlighted the place of “the economic development of the world as a whole. . . . [For] economic distress is a prime breeder of war.” IBRD, First Annual Meeting of the Board of Governors: Proceedings and Related Documents, 15 –16 (World Bank 1946). 3 Anne-Marie Leroy & Frank Fariello, The World Bank Group Sanctions Process and Its Recent Reforms 1 (World Bank 2012). 4 See IBRD Articles of Agreement, Article III, Section 5(b) (“The Bank shall make arrangements to ensure that the proceeds of any loan are used only for the purposes for which the loan was granted, with due attention to considerations of economy and efficiency and without regard to political or other non-economic influences or considerations”); and IDA Articles of Agreement, Article V, Section 6 (“The Association and its officers shall not interfere in the political affairs of any member; nor shall they be influenced in their decisions by the politi- cal character of the member or members concerned. Only economic considerations shall be relevant to their decisions, and these considerations shall be weighed impartially in order to achieve the purposes stated in this Agreement”). See also World Bank Sanctions Procedures (as adopted Apr. 15, 2012) (hereinafter, Sanctions Procedures), Article 1.01(a). 5 See, for example, News & Broadcast, World Bank, Disclosure of Assets and Income by Public Officials Is Crucial to Curbing Corruption Finds New StAR Study, Press Release No. 2012/360/ FPD (Mar. 28, 2012), available at http://go.worldbank.org/6JFJF7TXA0; Stuart Yikona et al., Ill-Gotten Money and the Economy, Experiences from Malawi and Namibia (World Bank 2011), available at http://go.worldbank.org/0PHO7X3QA0. See also C. M. Matthews, Infrastruc- ture Corruption Top of Mind for Public, Private Sectors, Wall St. J. (Apr. 19, 2012), available at http://blogs.wsj.com/corruption-currents/2012/04/19/infrastructure-corruption-top http://go.worldbank.org/6JFJF7TXA0 http://go.worldbank.org/0PHO7X3QA0 http://blogs.wsj.com/corruption-currents/2012/04/19/infrastructure-corruption-top-of-mind-for-public-private-sectors/ The World Bank Legal Review102 effect on systems and societies,6 they are the target of the Bank’s sanctions system. This chapter considers the Bank’s recent commitment to opening up its sanctions regime and to making that system more transparent and account- able, highlighting the particularly innovative manner in which the Bank has opened up its system. The desired end of this opening up is a sanctions regime that inspires confidence through the witnessing of the robust deliberative pro- cess that underlies it, the promotion of good governance at large, and an in- crease in stakeholder confidence. Opening up the process both encourages contractors to participate in Bank-financed projects and also garners further support for the fight against poverty by profiting those who play by the rules. The result is a system with significant due process protections that empowers stakeholders at all levels. This chapter is divided into four parts: • First, this chapter offers an introduction to the nature of the Bank’s sanc- tions regime, highlighting the particular challenges that it faces.7 • Second, it presents an outline of the development of the sanctions regime, focusing on the system’s rapid progression since its foundation in 1996. • Third, it addresses the most recent changes to the system. • Fourth, it examines how this progression is in accord with the Bank’s mis- sion of establishing law and justice as developmental ends in and of them- selves, with a special emphasis on transparency and accountability for the sake of improving both governance and stakeholder ownership and empowerment. The chapter concludes with remarks on the relationship between law and development and what that relationship means for the Bank as it seeks to em- power those for whom it works as well as to give them a sense of confidence in the Bank and the Bank’s systems as a whole. Introduction to the Bank’s Sanctions Regime Like other international financial institutions,8 the World Bank has tradi- tionally considered its decisions to exclude an entity or individual from work- -of-mind-for-public-private-sectors/; David Chaikin & J. C. Sharman, Corruption and Money Laundering: A Symbiotic Relationship (Palgrave Series on Asian Governance 2009); Dayanath Jayasuriya, Anti-Money Laundering Efforts, Stock Market Operations and Good Governance, 1 Qualitative Research in Financial Markets 46 –58 (2009). 6 See id. See also James D. Wolfensohn, People and Development: Address to the Board of Gover- nors at the Annual Meetings of the World Bank and the International Monetary Fund, in Voice for the World’s Poor: Selected Speeches and Writings of World Bank President James D. Wolfensohn, 1995–2005 50 (World Bank 2005). 7 For a detailed discussion of the historical system’s evolution, see Leroy & Fariello, supra note 3. 8 Consider, for instance, the other multilateral development banks (MDBs), discussed further on. See infra note 39. The same is true for many other international organizations, such as the United Nations and the North Atlantic Treaty Organization. http://blogs.wsj.com/corruption-currents/2012/04/19/infrastructure-corruption-top-of-mind-for-public-private-sectors/ Transforming through Transparency 103 ing on Bank-financed projects or programs as a business decision and has thus subjected those decisions to an administrative regime.9 That process of ex- clusion for corrupt or fraudulent behavior is known as “debarment.”10 The principal stated goal of World Bank Group sanctions proceedings is to protect the World Bank Group’s funds and not to “punish” respondents: the sanc- tions imposed do not entail any form of physical coercion, nor even an obliga- tion to repay money to the Bank.11 From such a perspective, relatively little due process12 is due to respondents as compared with during civil or criminal proceedings.13 There are, however, several factors that complicate the classification of such actions as otherwise-banal business decisions. First, with aggregate new lending commitments of approximately US$43 billion, aggregate outstanding liabilities of US$258 billion, and assets of US$314 billion for fiscal year 2011,14 and as the Bank directly or indirectly employs tens of thousands of people,15 9 See Leroy & Fariello, supra note 3. This model has not gone without criticism. See, for ex- ample, Alnoor Ebrhaim, The World Bank Must Fix Its Business Model, Financial Times (Oct. 5, 2009). 10 See Sanctions Procedures, supra note 4. 11 The Bank’s system allows for five different sanctions—reprimand, conditional nondebar- ment, debarment, debarment with conditional release, and restitution or remedy—only the last of which imposes the obligation of financial reparation. Sanctions Procedures, supra note 4, at Article 9. Of course, these stand apart from the typical contractual remedies available to the Bank under the general conditions. 12 Due process is the legal requirement that the sovereign respect the legal rights that are owed to persons; it is a “central promise [of] assurance that . . . government must operate within the law (‘legality’) and provide fair procedures.” Legal Information Institute (LII), Cornell University, at http://www.law.cornell.edu/wex/due_process. The principle ensures a bal- ancing of sovereign power (or the law of the land), on the one hand, and the rights of the individual, on the other. See, for example, In re Winship, 397 U.S. 358, 382 (1970) ( J. Black, dissenting). 13 As a body of public law, administrative law addresses and controls how government and its agencies govern. See William F. Fox, Jr., Understanding Administrative Law (4th ed., Lexis 2000). Generally, fewer rights are afforded to respondents in an administrative system than in civil or (especially) criminal proceedings; in administrative proceedings, the interests and prerogatives of the sovereign and the invocation of its discretionary powers are at stake. 14 See Moody’s Investors Service Credit Analysis: IBRD (World Bank) (Feb. 27, 2012), available at http://treasury.worldbank.org/cmd/pdf/Moodys_IBRD_Report_2012.pdf. The Bank also provides financing in the form of development policy loans (DPLs), which provide bud- get support and other unlinked financing against achievement of defined policy measures rather than to finance specific expenditures. The Bank’s sanctions regime does not extend to DPLs because it is not possible to trace the use of loan proceeds. This approach (or the lack of one) has come under increasing criticism. See, for example, Independent Advisory Board (IAB), 2010 Annual Report 11-12 ( Jan. 2011), available at http://go.worldbank.org /S262CF3KD0 (acknowledging the “significant challenges and difficulties concerning efforts to investigate the extent, if any, of corrupt behaviors that may arise in connection with the implementation of [DPLs],” but encouraging management “to consider ways and means of sharpening the criteria for [DPLs]”). It bears noting that the effect of cross-debarment renders the figures—and the effect of debarment—even greater. See infra note 40 et seq. and accompanying text. 15 Moisés Naím & Uri Dadush, Dr. Kim Comes to Washington, Huffington Post (Apr. 4, 2012), avail- able at http://www.huffingtonpost.com/moises-naim/kim-world-bank_b_1396618.html. http://www.law.cornell.edu/wex/due_process http://treasury.worldbank.org/cmd/pdf/Moodys_IBRD_Report_2012.pdf http://go.worldbank.org/S262CF3KD0 http://www.huffingtonpost.com/moises-naim/kim-world-bank_b_1396618.html http://go.worldbank.org/S262CF3KD0 The World Bank Legal Review104 the stakes of exclusion from Bank-financed projects are substantially higher than those surrounding even the most significant business decisions made by the largest private corporations.16 Moreover, debarment not only entails substantial financial consequences but also causes considerable public noto- riety and reputational damage.17 Second, debarring an entity has significant market effects, especially when a limited number of entities are capable of per- forming highly specialized work.18 Third, the Bank’s decision to debar is not one that affects those entities with which the Bank itself would otherwise work, but rather affects the pool of entities from which the borrower might choose to work; that is, the Bank, on the basis of providing project financing, unilaterally decides for the borrowing party that certain entities are not to be dealt with.19 16 That is to say, the economic implications of exclusion from the possibility of participating in the large potential market of World Bank Group–financed projects are greater than those of being excluded from the activities of any one private actor. For instance, to make a mon- etary comparison, the market value of Apple in 2011, the world’s most valuable company, is around US$337 million, with 12-month sales surpassing the US$100 billion mark. Scott DeCarlo, The World’s 25 Most Valuable Companies: Apple Is Now on Top, Forbes (Aug. 11, 2011), available at http://www.forbes.com/sites/scottdecarlo/2011/08/11/the-worlds-25-most -valuable-companies-apple-is-now-on-top/. 17 Consider, for instance, the press coverage surrounding the sanctioning of Siemens. See, for example, Siemens Selects Initial Projects for US$100 million Integrity Initiative, Siemens AG, Ref. No. AXX20101225e (Dec. 9, 2010), available at http://www.siemens.com/press/en /pressrelease/?press=/en/pressrelease/2010/corporate_communication/axx20101225.htm; Vanessa Fuhrmans, Siemens Settles with World Bank on Bribes, Wall St. J. ( Jul. 3, 2009), available at http://online.wsj.com/article/SB124655953719287521.html. 18 In this regard, consider, for instance, the debarment of a Siemens subsidiary. See News & Broadcast, World Bank, World Bank Group Debars Limited Liability Company Siemens (OOO Siemens) for Engaging in Fraud and Corruption in a World Bank–Financed Project in Rus- sia, Press Release No. 2009/168/EXC (Nov. 30, 2009), available at http://go.worldbank .org/VZ1113XEG0. In addition to having a subsidiary entity debarred, Siemens AG paid US$100 million to fight corruption as part of a settlement with the World Bank Group. See News & Broadcast, World Bank, Siemens to Pay $100m to Fight Corruption as Part of World Bank Group Settlement, Press Release No. 2009/001/EXT ( Jul. 2, 2009), available at http:// go.worldbank.org/WXRNSDVI40. Siemens, France’s Alstom, and Canada’s Bombardier are the world’s big-three passenger train manufacturers. See, for example, Robert Wright, China to Loosen West’s Grip on Rail Sector, Financial Times (Sept. 13, 2010), available at http://www .ft.com/intl/cms/s/0/83d7e478-bec0-11df-a755-00144feab49a.html#axzz1sKPOrVA4. For the argument that certain private contractors may be too big to debar, see Drury D. Steven & Nicholas J. Wagoner, FCPA Sanctions: Too Big to Debar? 80 Fordham L. Rev. 775 (2011). See also FCPA Compliance and Ethics Blog, Is Debarment a Viable FCPA Enforcement Option? (Apr. 19, 2011), available at http://tfoxlaw.wordpress.com/2011/04/19/is-debarment-a-viable-fcpa -enforcement-option/. 19 Others, for reasons such as the absence of privity and the substantial influence that the Bank is capable of exerting, have described the Bank’s behavior as “imperialism” or “neocolonial- ism.” Catherine Caufield, Masters of Illusion: The World Bank and the Poverty of Nations (Henry Holt & Co. 1996); Jonathan Cahn, Challenging the New Imperial Authority: The World Bank and the Democratization of Development, 6 Harv. Hum. Rights J. 159 (1993); Steve Berkman, The World Bank and the Gods of Lending (Kumarian Press 2008); Payal Parekh & Oren Weinrib, Why the Developing World Hates the World Bank, 122 The Tech 5 (Mar. 12, 2002), available at http:// tech.mit.edu/V122/PDF/N11.pdf. http://www.forbes.com/sites/scottdecarlo/2011/08/11/the-worlds-25-most-valuable-companies-apple-is-now-on-top/ http://www.siemens.com/press/en/pressrelease/?press=/en/pressrelease/2010/corporate_communication/axx20101225.htm http://online.wsj.com/article/SB124655953719287521.html http://go.worldbank.org/VZ1113XEG0 http://go.worldbank.org/VZ1113XEG0 http://www.ft.com/intl/cms/s/0/83d7e478-bec0-11df-a755-00144feab49a.html#axzz1sKPOrVA4 http://www.ft.com/intl/cms/s/0/83d7e478-bec0-11df-a755-00144feab49a.html#axzz1sKPOrVA4 http://tfoxlaw.wordpress.com/2011/04/19/is-debarment-a-viable-fcpa-enforcement-option/ http://www.forbes.com/sites/scottdecarlo/2011/08/11/the-worlds-25-most-valuable-companies-apple-is-now-on-top/ http://www.siemens.com/press/en/pressrelease/?press=/en/pressrelease/2010/corporate_communication/axx20101225.htm http://go.worldbank.org/WXRNSDVI40 http://go.worldbank.org/WXRNSDVI40 http://tfoxlaw.wordpress.com/2011/04/19/is-debarment-a-viable-fcpa-enforcement-option/ http://tech.mit.edu/V122/PDF/N11.pdf http://tech.mit.edu/V122/PDF/N11.pdf Transforming through Transparency 105 Thus, Bank operational debarments—taken in the absence of any privity—are more than mere run-of-the-mill business decisions about, say, buying pens or paper.20 Although none of the aforementioned factors necessarily takes the Bank’s regime out of the realm of administrative law, the Bank, in an effort to lead by example, and considering law and justice as developmental ends in and of themselves, affords respondents additional due process protections, more than what are usually required under the general principles of administra- tive law.21 Arguments have been made that the World Bank Group’s system ought to develop its legal regime based on, alternatively, theories of global constitutionalism,22 the exercise of international public authority,23 or the emerging global administrative law (GAL) principles.24 The Bank has taken a more open-ended approach by working toward a quasi-judicial model in- spired by various sources of law from around the world. Such an innovative approach results in a sui generis form that is not dominated by any single tradition (neither common law nor civil law) or by any one national system. In pursuing the objectives of effectiveness and efficiency, the Bank has been equally attentive to ensuring that the process reflects certain fundamental 20 It is worth noting that the World Bank Group maintains a separate sanctions system for its own corporate procurement. See World Bank Vendor Eligibility Policy (as adopted Jun. 18, 2010), available at http://go.worldbank.org/W40WJB5AA0. To be deemed a re- sponsible vendor with whom the World Bank Group will conduct business, a vendor must meet a range of standards, most of which relate to the financial and organizational capacity of the vendor to deliver or perform the services, as well as its track record in not having seri- ously violated the terms of a World Bank Group contract in the past. In addition, a vendor must not have committed “any act or offense indicating a lack of integrity or honesty that seriously and directly affects [its] present responsibility . . . , including fraudulent, corrupt, collusive, coercive, or obstructive practices.” 21 “‘Respondent’ means an entity or individual alleged to have engaged in a Sanctionable Prac- tice and who has been designated as such in a Notice.” Sanctions Procedures, supra note 4, at Article 1.02. 22 See Jan Klabbers, Anne Petters, & Geir Ulfstein, The Constitutionalization of International Law (Oxford U. Press 2009). 23 See Armin von Bogdandy, Philipp Dann, & Matthias Goldmann, Developing the Publicness of Public International Law: Towards a Legal Framework for Global Governance Activities, 9 German L.J. 1375, 1377 (2008) (“The legal framework of governance activities of international institu- tions should be conceived of as international institutional law, and enriched by a public law perspective, i.e. with constitutional sensibility and openness for comparative insights from administrative legal thinking”), and the other articles in the same special issue on public authority and international institutions. 24 See Benedict Kingsbury, Nico Krisch, & Richard B. Stewart, The Emergence of Global Admin- istrative Law, 16 L. & Contemp. Probs. 15, 17 (2005) (defining global administrative law “as comprising the mechanisms, principles, practices, and supporting social understandings that promote or otherwise affect the accountability of global administrative bodies, in par- ticular by ensuring they meet adequate standards of transparency, participation, reasoned decision, and legality, and by providing effective review of the rules and decisions they make”), and the other articles in the same symposium. See also articles in the symposium Global Administrative Law in the Operations of International Organizations in 6 Intl. Org. L. Rev. (2009); Pascale Hélène Dubois & Aileen Elizabeth Nowlan, Global Administrative Law and the Legitimacy of Sanctions Regimes in International Law, 36 Yale J. Intl. L. 15–25 (2010). http://go.worldbank.org/W40WJB5AA0 The World Bank Legal Review106 principles and values associated with the rule of law from around the world.25 In so doing, it is particularly mindful of the varied—and ever-evolving—le- gal traditions and conceptions of its members.26 Such a creative approach gives the Bank’s system a certain formality while allowing it to retain a nec- essary flexibility.27 That flexibility is particularly useful in dealing with par- ties coming from different developmental backgrounds. The unique mix of formality and flexibility is a development of the Bank’s legal heritage that goes beyond traditional understandings of either civil or common law.28 This legal innovation—with its sensitivity to culture and tradition and its imple- mentation of robust due process guarantees—is particularly important in a world where international organizations (IOs) are increasingly helping to form international law.29 The system’s evolution, with its progressive permutations and additions, has made the regime increasingly robust and juridical. Although it was not the intention of the framers that the Bank’s system be overly “legalistic,”30 such an evolution is an almost-inevitable by-product of a two-tiered adversarial process that allows for legal representation and, more recently, publication of reasoned decision making.31 The Bank has instituted these structural changes in the spirit of due process and of rule of law. Although this judicialization has had the unintended consequence of increasing the system’s intricacy—a 25 Leroy & Fariello, supra note 3, at 6–7. Elements of the rule of law are embedded in the writ- ings of modern and Western political philosophers such as Locke, Montesquieu, Ricardo, and Weber. More broadly, a concept of the rule of law is inherent in natural law ideals as expressed by Aristotle and Aquinas, as well as in religiously inspired legal systems such as Islamic sharia. As far back as the third century B.C., the Chinese legal thinker Han Fei pro- moted the view that laws had to be predictable, public, and consistent. 26 See supra note 25 and accompanying text. See Karen Gottschang Turner, Rule of Law, in The Oxford International Encyclopedia of Legal History vol. V, 164 (Stanley N. Katz ed., Oxford U. Press 2009). 27 For an instance of such duality considered in the US national context of prosecution and prosecutorial discretion, see Nathan Piwowarski, Prosecutorial Discretion and the Rule of Law: Is It Time for a Little Formalism? (Or, Mr. Prosecutor: How Formalists Learned to Stop Worrying and Love Discretion), King Scholar Senior Seminar Paper, Michigan State University College of Law (2007), available at http://www.law.msu.edu/king/2007/index.html. 28 Robert D. Cooter & Hans-Bernd Schafer, Solomon’s Knot: How Law Can End the Poverty of Na- tions 94–95 (Princeton U. Press 2012). 29 See, for example, José E. Alarez, International Organizations as Law-Makers (Oxford U. Press 2005). 30 See, for example, Dick Thornburgh, Ronald L. Gainer, & Cuyler H. Walker, Report Concern- ing the Debarment Processes of the World Bank (Aug. 14, 2002 [Rev.]), available at http:// go.worldbank.org/1O93GTKH40 (hereinafter, Second Thornburgh Report) at 27 (“[I]t should be kept in mind that the Sanctions Committee procedures are designed and intended to be very informal and avoid unnecessary legal complexities. For that reason, circumspec- tion should be employed in evaluating former judges and litigating attorneys—persons whose careers have been steeped in the mastery of formal hearing procedures of particular national jurisdictions and who are thus more likely than others (for example those whose primary experience has been with informal arbitration proceedings or administrative pro- ceedings) to exhibit a penchant for procedural formality and rigidity”). 31 Leroy & Fariello, supra note 3, at 28. http://www.law.msu.edu/king/2007/index.html http://go.worldbank.org/1O93GTKH40 http://go.worldbank.org/1O93GTKH40 Transforming through Transparency 107 weight that weighs most heavily on lesser-capacity respondents—that same augmentation of due process protections has the benefit of assuring all re- spondents ever-greater protection, therein helping to ensure that respondents have an opportunity to have their full and fair day in court. Respondents need not fear lengthy proceedings; despite its evolution toward greater due pro- cess, the Bank’s sanctions process remains far more expeditious than national court systems.32 The Innovative History of the Bank’s Ever-Expanding Sanctions Regime Year by year, the Bank’s system has become more expansive and innovative, providing an ever more complete means of protecting the Bank and the projects that it finances from the deleterious effects of fraud and corruption. Initiated in 1996,33 the implementation of the Bank’s sanctions regime coincided with an increased focus on corruption as a development issue.34 Since its inception, the Bank’s sanctions regime has grown dramatically: in 1999, only corrup- tion, fraud, and collusion were referred to in the Procurement and Consultant Guidelines.35 In 2004, “coercive practice” was added to this list of “sanction- able practices,” therein prohibiting the threatening of competing bidders, gov- ernment officials, or others.36 In 2006, a fifth rubric of “obstructive practices” was added to the guidelines and targets actions that impede an investigation, such as destroying evidence or threatening witnesses.37 Moreover, the regime was expanded beyond fraud and corruption in the limited area of the procure- ment context alone to cover all fraud and corruption that may occur in connec- tion with the use of Bank financing in the preparation and/or implementation of Bank-financed projects at large.38 These reforms were accompanied by new 32 On average, a sanctions case (excluding investigation) takes approximately one year. When a case is not appealed to the Sanctions Board, the median time for sanctions proceedings is about six months. 33 Second Thornburgh Report, supra note 30, at 12. 34 See Leroy & Fariello, supra note 3, at 9. 35 All current and historical guidelines are available at the World Bank website. See World Bank, Guidelines: Selection and Employment of Consultants by World Bank Borrowers, sec- tion 1.22 (Oct. 1, 2006), available at http://go.worldbank.org/U9IPSLUDC0 (hereinafter, Consultant Guidelines); World Bank, Guidelines: Procurement under IBRD Loans and IDA Credits, section 1.14 (May 1, 2010), available at http://go.worldbank.org/1KKD1KNT40 (hereinafter, Procurement Guidelines). 36 Reform of the World Bank’s Sanctions Process ( Jun. 28, 2004), Policies Guiding INT’s Work, World Bank, available at http://go.worldbank.org/VVY6KYS720. 37 Expansion of Sanction beyond Procurement and Sanctioning of Obstructive Practices ( Jul. 28, 2006), Policies Guiding INT’s Work, World Bank, available at http://go.worldbank.org /VVY6KYS720. 38 See President’s Memorandum to the Executive Directors, Sanctions Reform: Expansion of Sanc- tions Regime beyond Procurement and Sanctioning of Obstructive Practices ( Jun. 12, 2006). Con- currently, amended sanctions procedures were adopted, reflecting both the 2004 and the 2006 rounds of sanctions reform. http://go.worldbank.org/U9IPSLUDC0 http://go.worldbank.org/1KKD1KNT40 http://go.worldbank.org/VVY6KYS720 http://go.worldbank.org/VVY6KYS720 http://go.worldbank.org/VVY6KYS720 The World Bank Legal Review108 harmonized definitions of the first four sanctionable practices, as used by all of the five major multilateral development banks (MDBs).39 In 2010, in a move that further expanded the system, the Bank signed a cross-debarment accord with the other four major MDBs,40 allowing for the signatories to cross-debar firms and individuals found to have engaged in wrongdoing in MDB-financed development projects.41 Not only did this agreement establish the first four sanctionable practices as common among the five MDBs (as already noted); it also codified a common standard of proof, namely, the “more likely than not”42 standard.43 The Bank is constantly monitoring the implementation of its sanctions framework with a view to improving its effectiveness and efficiency, in dia- logue with all internal actors as well as with the other major MDBs and other IOs. Similarly, the Bank is always looking for inspiration to improve transpar- ency and fairness. This chronological development has been presented without any reference to the infrastructural developments; a few notes ought to be made. The sys- tem began in 1998 with relatively few structural due process checks and bal- 39 See Uniform Framework for Preventing and Combating Fraud and Corruption, Interna- tional Financial Institutions Anti-corruption Task Force (Sep. 2006), available at http:// go.worldbank.org/VVY6KYS720. The agreement includes the African Development Bank, the Asian Development Bank, the European Bank for Reconstruction and Development, the Inter-American Development Bank Group, and the World Bank Group. 40 See News & Broadcast, World Bank, Cross-Debarment Accord Steps Up Fight against Corrup- tion (Apr. 9, 2010), available at http://go.worldbank.org/B699B73Q00. See also Integrity Vice Presidency Annual Report, Fiscal Year 2008: Protecting Development’s Potential 2 (World Bank INT 2009), available at http://go.worldbank.org/T40HHT3RF0. 41 See World Bank, Cross-Debarment Accord Steps Up Fight against Corruption, supra note 40; In- tegrity Vice Presidency Annual Report, Fiscal Year 2008, supra note 40. See also Stephen S. Zim- mermann & Frank A. Fariello, Coordinating the Fight against Fraud and Corruption: Agreement on Cross-Debarment among Multilateral Development Banks, in International Financial Institutions and Global Legal Governance (Hassane Cissé, Daniel D. Bradlow, & Benedict Kingsbury ed., World Bank 2011). Cross-debarment is permitted for any of the first four sanctionable prac- tices, namely, corruption, fraud, collusion, and coercive practices. 42 See Sanctions Procedures, supra note 4, at Article 8.01(b)(i). See also Anne-Marie Leroy, Ad- visory Opinion on Certain Issues Arising in Connection with Recent Sanctions Cases, No. 2010/1 (Nov. 15, 2010), paragraphs 45–51, in the UN Juridical Yearbook 2012 (“The standard of proof is predicated on the same basic considerations that underlay the omission of an explicit mens rea requirement from most of the definitions, namely the administrative nature of the proceedings and INT’s lack of investigative tools. This standard of proof is understood as being equivalent to the ‘preponderance of the evidence,’ essentially the standard to be found in civil cases in most jurisdictions. When this nomenclature was adopted in 2004, it was felt that the phrase ‘more likely than not’ would be more understandable to non-lawyers. How- ever, the ‘more than 50%’ approach may not be the most useful or appropriate either at the EO stage or at the Sanctions Board stage. Firstly, it suggests a formulaic approach to the evi- dence while . . . the Sanctions Procedures calls for a discretionary approach. [Secondly . . .], the EO’s assessment of the evidence requires special considerations, given that he or she is looking at only one side of the case. The EO is actually charged with assessing the sufficiency of the evidence”), 43 World Bank, Cross-Debarment Accord Steps Up Fight against Corruption, supra note 40. http://go.worldbank.org/VVY6KYS720 http://go.worldbank.org/B699B73Q00 http://go.worldbank.org/T40HHT3RF0.41 http://go.worldbank.org/VVY6KYS720 Transforming through Transparency 109 ances; an entirely internal sanctions committee reviewed allegations of fraud and corruption and recommended an appropriate sanction to the president of the Bank, who made the actual decision.44 In 2001, a nascent yet independent prosecutorial and investigatory branch, the Integrity Vice Presidency (INT), was established, therein consolidating functions that had been spread across various units of the Bank.45 INT was one of the first specialized units created specifically to address fraud and corruption allegations and integrity issues at an international level.46 The system evolved into its current two-tiered process in 2007, with an initial determination made by the Evaluation and Suspen- sion Officer (EO) and with the possibility of a de novo review by the World Bank Sanctions Board.47 Further modifications were made to assure the inde- pendence and adequacy of the various actors,48 and measures for controlling lingering vulnerabilities at either end of the sanctions process were added.49 Additional added features include the means of sanctioning corporate affili- ates50 and the possibility of resolving disputes through settlement (termed as “negotiated resolution agreements” and “deferral agreements,” depending on the type of settlement).51 Given that the regime is inherently an administrative one, the Bank’s sanctions system has evolved into one that affords respondents substantial 44 See Leroy & Fariello, supra note 3, at 10. See also Ko-Yung Tung, General Counsel, World Bank, The World Bank’s Institutional Framework for Combating Fraud and Corruption, remarks delivered at the Seminar on Monetary and Financial Law International Monetary Fund (May 8, 2002). 45 The then Department of Institutional Integrity was given institutional independence and reported directly to the president. See, for example, Ko-Yung Tung, remarks delivered at the Seminar on Monetary and Financial Law International Monetary Fund (May 8, 2002). 46 Although the UN Office of Internal Oversight Services was created somewhat earlier (1994), that office has a much more general mandate than does INT. See UN Office of Internal Over- sight Services at http://www.un.org/Depts/oios/. 47 See Leroy & Fariello, supra note 3, at 10–11. 48 See, for example, Paul A. Volcker et al., Independent Panel Review of World Bank Group Depart- ment of Institutional Integrity (Sep. 13, 2007) (recommending, among other things, that INT be elevated to the status of a vice presidency with reporting lines directly to the president, as well as the creation of the external Independent Advisory Board to facilitate oversight of INT). 49 Inefficiencies and lingering vulnerabilities undermined the effectiveness of the system, both at the “front end” (for example, firms under investigation remain eligible to bid for Bank- financed contracts) and at the “back end” (for example, sanctioned firms were normally re- leased from debarment without any demonstration of rehabilitation). These weaknesses led to the implementation of, first, in May 2009, the possibility for INT to request early tempo- rary sanctions for the time prior to the commencement of formal proceedings, and, second, the institution of the Integrity Compliance Office, which provided guidance to sanctioned parties and monitored implementation of respondents’ compliance programs. For more, see Leroy & Fariello, supra note 3, at 12–17. The drive for greater efficiency also led the Bank to consider and then pilot negotiated resolutions to sanctions cases (aka settlements) in lieu of full-blown sanctions proceedings. 50 See Leroy & Fariello, supra note 3, at 17–18. 51 Sanctions Procedures, supra note 4, at Article XI. See Leroy & Fariello, supra note 3, at 20–22. http://www.un.org/Depts/oios/ The World Bank Legal Review110 procedural protections.52 Indeed, in a comparative study with the other major MDBs and with other IOs, the Bank’s procedures are substantially more elabo- rate.53 The Bank, with different needs and with a greater variety of interests than most other IOs, has deemed such provisions to be well merited: on the one hand, the Bank funds a diversity of projects in a diversity of places, im- plicating stakeholders around the world; on the other hand, more than half of respondents are sanctioned by default because they do not respond in any way to notices of sanctions proceedings, and only one-third of respondents appeal the EO’s recommended sanction.54 Moreover, recognizing that due process standards are not ubiquitous,55 the Bank has not created a one-size- fits-all system: although operating within the expeditious contours of an ad- ministrative model, the Bank has developed a series of gradations within its regime. Thus, at one end of the spectrum, the system allows for more expedi- ent processing when allegations are less serious and when the corresponding due process requirements are less onerous; at the other extreme, when allega- tions are considerably weightier, the full system, with all of its incumbent due process guarantees, is engaged. Such legal innovations allow the Bank to more attentively engage respondents while fulfilling its fiduciary duty. The Commitment to Transparency: An Ever-Improving System The Bank’s decision to increase due process protections for respondents in its sanctions regime is doubly beneficial. First, it ensures that the Bank appro- priately fulfills its fiduciary duty under its Articles of Agreement.56 Second, it corresponds with the Bank’s emerging role of seeking to encourage not only economic development but also the growth of socially accountable societies founded on and embracing law and justice.57 As this edition of the World Bank 52 See Fox, supra note 13. See also, Second Thornburgh Report, supra note 30 at 2 et seq. 53 See Zimmermann & Fariello, supra note 41. 54 Dubois & Nowlan, supra note 24, at 21–22. 55 See discussion of due process at note 12. The US Supreme Court has said that due process, “unlike some legal rules, is not a technical conception with a fixed content unrelated to time, place and circumstances.” Matthews v. Eldridge, 424 U.S. 319, 334 (1975) (quoting Cafeteria Workers v. McElroy, 367 U.S. 886, 895 [1961], describing the flexibility of due process). The court highlighted the flexibility of the notion by continuing that its protections are required only when the “particular situation demands” (quoting Morrissey v. Brewer, 408 U.S. 471, 481 [1972]). 56 IBRD Articles of Agreement, supra note 4, at Article III, Section 5(b), and IDA Articles of Agreement, supra note 4, at Article V, Section 1(g). 57 See News & Broadcast, World Bank, The Global Partnership for Social Accountability: A New Mechanism to Support Civil Society Organizations, Press Release No. 2012/406/WBI (Apr. 19, 2012), available at http://go.worldbank.org/1393388IP0; Hassane Cissé, Conflict, Fragility and Development in a Globalized World: Challenges and Implications for the Law of the Future, 4th HiiL Law of the Future Conference ( Jun. 23, 2011) (“[D]iverse . . . forms of violence result in fragility, or the weakening, diminishing and destruction of institutions that would other- wise contain conflicts and resolve injustice peacefully. This definition of fragility constitutes the flip side of what has been defined as ‘rule of law’”); Q&A with Hassane Cissé, Global Forum: How Open Data Links Rule of Law to Economic Growth, East African (Apr. 9 –15, 2012) http://go.worldbank.org/1393388IP0 Transforming through Transparency 111 Legal Review so clearly shows, and as this chapter emphasizes with regard to a specific facet of the Bank’s activities, law and justice are not merely means to an end but are themselves ends, albeit ends that will further other developmental ends, such as economic growth.58 Such theories of inclusive development are not new,59 although they are (relatively) new in their implementation.60 The Bank’s vision of inclusive growth and development—that is, broad- based investment in human beings61—is one that the Bank has embraced at large.62 This vision is apparent in the World Bank Inspection Panel, which en- sures that a voice is afforded to those affected by Bank-financed projects in which there has been a breach of Bank protocol.63 The vision dovetails with (“Business actors need to trust [governmental and social] institutions, and especially judicial institutions. The system has to be robust, efficient and respond to people’s needs. If business people don’t trust that rulings will be timely and just, they will find other ways to solve disputes. More often than not, they will prefer to bypass the justice system and buy out- comes—in other words, resort to corruption. This spills over beyond the business sector and becomes a social problem, setting the clock back for development. . . . A working system has to be fair, transparent, accessible to everyone, and timely. . . . Only then can we have tools to hold government accountable, so that concepts like the rule of law, justice, social inclusion, empowerment and accountability move beyond simple words to become reality, and part and parcel of the development process”). See also Justin Yifu Lin, Demystifying Success: The New Structural Economics Approach (World Bank Apr. 2011); Siobhán McInerney-Lankford & Hans-Otto Sano, Human Rights Indicators in Development: An Introduction (World Bank 2010). 58 See, for example, Justin Yifu Lin and Célestin Monga, The Growth Report and New Structural Economics (World Bank 2010); Q&A with Hassane Cissé, supra note 57 (“Development goes beyond providing economic growth. It has to address equity, equality and justice, and these are at the heart of the rule of law. If these are not dealt with, you don’t have the foundation for economic development”). See also Cooter & Schafer, supra note 28. 59 For example, see David M. Trubek & Marc Galanter, Scholars in Self-Estrangement: Some Re- flections on the Crisis in Law and Development Studies in the United States, 4 Wis. L. Rev. 1062 (1974); Richard A. Posner, Creating a Legal Framework for Economic Development, 13 World Bank Research Observer 1 (1998); Hernando de Soto, The Other Path: The Economic Answer to Terrorism (Basic Books 1989); Amartya Sen, Development as Freedom (Knopf 1999); Kaushik Basu & Ravi Kanbur ed., Arguments for a Better World: Essays in Honor of Amartya Sen (Oxford U. Press 2009). See also Cooter & Schafer, supra note 28. 60 Although the Bank has long acknowledged the important role of civil society and has worked with civil society organizations for decades, having, for example, established what would be called the Civil Society Fund in 1983, the Bank has stepped up efforts and is committed to such activities and to such development. The Global Partnership for Social Accountability, supra note 57. See also Lin and Monga, supra note 58. 61 See Elena Ianchovichina, Susanna Lundstrom, & Leonardo Garrido, What Is Inclusive Growth? PRMED Knowledge Brief (Feb. 10, 2009), available at http://go.worldbank.org /LG5Z4L6LR0. See also Jim Yong Kim, My Call for an Open, Inclusive World Bank, Financial Times (Mar. 28, 2012). 62 World Bank, The Growth Report: Strategies for Sustained Growth and Inclusive Development (World Bank 2008); Lin and Monga, supra note 58, at 14 (“Long-term sustainable and in- clusive growth is the driving force for poverty reduction in developing countries, and for convergence with developed economies”). 63 Inspection Panel, World Bank, at http://www.inspectionpanel.org/. The Inspection Panel is an independent, “bottom-up” accountability and recourse mechanism that investigates IBRD/IDA-financed projects to determine whether the Bank has complied with its opera- tional policies and procedures (including social and environmental safeguards), and to ad- dress related issues of harm. http://go.worldbank.org//LG5Z4L6LR0 http://www.inspectionpanel.org/ http://go.worldbank.org//LG5Z4L6LR0 The World Bank Legal Review112 the selection of Dr. Jim Yong Kim,64 a medical doctor and developmentalist, as president rather than the more traditional choice of an economist or of a politician.65 Similarly, it is a motivating factor behind the Global Forum for Law, Justice and Development, of which the Bank will serve as Secretariat, and which aims to support the development of strong legal and judicial insti- tutions by sharing and generating knowledge through international collabo- ration.66 In the spirit of improving social accountability,67 among other things, the Bank has worked vigorously to develop means of measuring success be- yond traditional economic metrics; critically, it is tying these new measures to governance and anticorruption strategies.68 The key tool therein is transpar- ency; as US Supreme Court justice Louis Brandeis once quipped, “Sunlight is . . . the best disinfectant.”69 64 See, for example, Obama Nominates Dartmouth President Jim Yong Kim to Lead World Bank, Time (Mar. 23, 2012) (“Officials believe [Kim’s] experience will help counter criticism from developing countries that have grown weary of the U.S. stranglehold on the World Bank presidency”). See also News & Broadcast, World Bank, World Bank’s Executive Directors Select Dr. Jim Yong Kim 12th President of the World Bank Group, Press Release No. 2012/395/SEC (Apr. 16, 2012), available at http://go.worldbank.org/AX89KWI2H0. 65 Annie Lowrey, College President Is Obama’s Pick for World Bank Chief, NY Times (Mar. 23, 2012), available at http://www.nytimes.com/2012/03/24/business/global/dartmouth -president-is-obamas-pick-for-world-bank.html. Kim’s acceptance is striking because he has openly—and articulately—challenged “[t]he idea that robust economic growth will au- tomatically lead to a better life for everybody” and has even gone so far as to argue that “the structure and current rules of today’s market-led economic globalization [that is, in 2000] widen the chasm between the privileged and the destitute, imperiling the lives of the world’s poor.” See Jim Yong Kim et al. ed., Dying for Growth: Global Inequality and the Health of the Poor 7, 3 (Common Courage Press 2000). A better metric for the success of development, Kim et al. argue, is “[f]ocusing on health rather than other traditional indicators of wealth.” Kim’s unorthodox background led both to considerable criticism of his nomination (Hats Off to Ngozi: A Golden Opportunity for the Rest of the World to Show Barack Obama the Mean- ing of Meritocracy, The Economist [Mar. 31, 2012]) and to much praise (Thomas J. Bollyky, How to Fix the World Bank, NY Times [Apr. 8, 2012]); Gillian Tett, Right Time for a World Bank Renaissance Man, Financial Times [Mar. 30, 2012]). Kim has responded to criticism by saying that his thoughts in 2000 are not applicable: “Our concern [in 2000] was that the vision was not inclusive enough, that it wasn’t, in the bank’s words, ‘pro-poor.’ The bank has shifted tremendously since that time, and now the notion of pro-poor development is at the core of the World Bank.” Annie Lowrey, Obama Candidate Sketches Vision for World Bank, NY Times (Apr. 9, 2012). Kim has also noted that his top priority is “spurring economic growth that creates jobs.” Nicole Kekeh, Dr. Kim Wins Top Job at the World Bank, Forbes (Apr. 17, 2012), available at http://www.forbes.com/sites/worldviews/2012/04/17/dr-kim-wins-top-job -at-the-world-bank-promises-inclusive-leadership/. 66 Charter of the Global Forum for Law, Justice and Development. 67 See, for example, World Bank president Robert Zoellick’s comments on the need to “democ- ratize development” in his Peterson Institute for International Economics speech, The Middle East and North Africa: A New Social Contract for Development (Apr. 6, 2011), available at http:// go.worldbank.org/QQ10SJQOJ0; see also Robert Zoellick’s talk at the conference “Support- ing Social Accountability for Better Results” (Apr. 19, 2012). 68 The Global Partnership for Social Accountability, supra note 57. See also Governance and Anti- corruption Key Principles, Governance & Anticorruption, World Bank, available at http:// go.worldbank.org/32PINXVIJ0; Beyond Transparency: What’s Next? Governance for Develop- ment, available at http://blogs.worldbank.org/governance/beyond-transparency-what -s-next. 69 Other People’s Money and How the Bankers Use It 13 (Frederick A. Stokes Co. 1913). http://go.worldbank.org/AX89KWI2H0.65 http://www.nytimes.com/2012/03/24/business/global/dartmouth-president-is-obamas-pick-for-world-bank.html http://www.forbes.com/sites/worldviews/2012/04/17/dr-kim-wins-top-job-at-the-world-bank-promises-inclusive-leadership/ http://blogs.worldbank.org/governance/beyond-transparency-what-s-next http://www.nytimes.com/2012/03/24/business/global/dartmouth-president-is-obamas-pick-for-world-bank.html http://www.forbes.com/sites/worldviews/2012/04/17/dr-kim-wins-top-job-at-the-world-bank-promises-inclusive-leadership/ http://go.worldbank.org/QQ10SJQOJ0 http://go.worldbank.org/QQ10SJQOJ0 http://blogs.worldbank.org/governance/beyond-transparency-what-s-next http://go.worldbank.org/32PINXVIJ0 http://go.worldbank.org/32PINXVIJ0 Transforming through Transparency 113 In this vein, the Bank is contemplating further reforms to its sanctions regime, with particular emphasis on improving transparency and participa- tion—both of the sanctions process itself and of the policy making that sur- rounds it—as well as due process protections, and exploring ways to afford better access to low-capacity respondents. Although there is more to be done, the Bank has attempted to remain true to its calling to empower the disem- powered. This cyclical process results in ever-greater legitimacy of the Bank and its sanctions regime, as well as in greater efficiency and effectiveness. The Legal Orientation of the Bank’s Sanctions Regime: Toward Ever-Better Governance The Bank’s current system draws from different legal disciplines, not reflect- ing any single national system, or even any single legal tradition—indeed, that is the point. With stakeholders around the world, the World Bank con- tinually strives to remain both global and worldly—that is, to represent the communities of the world while remaining not merely relevant but vibrant in a developmental sea populated by multiple players of all sizes.70 In devel- oping its own system, the Bank draws from both common law and civil law traditions, as well as looking to national systems for inspiration. The Bank’s incorporation of elements on the basis of efficiency and effectiveness has al- lowed it to create its own sui generis tradition, a tradition that operates best in this transnational space where IOs are increasingly developing the meaning of international law.71 Moreover, legal diversification has the added bonus of allaying potential perceptions that the Bank is biased in favor of any given na- tional system. This sui generis system is a major legal innovation that allows the Bank, notwithstanding its size, to bring an impressive degree of particular- ity, precision, and attention to its dealings with varied stakeholders. To understand the orientation and nature of the Bank’s sanctions system, one must understand that the ultimate aim of the system is not to punish but rather to correct and rehabilitate: the system seeks to reintroduce those enti- ties that have been implicated in fraudulent or corrupt behavior back into the market after a certain minimum period of debarment and upon adoption of adequate and effective policies and measures to guard against future miscon- duct.72 Thus, the system’s baseline sanction is “debarment with conditional 70 See, for example, Robert B. Zoellick, Why We Still Need the World Bank: Looking beyond Aid, Foreign Affairs (Mar./Apr. 2012), available at http://go.worldbank.org/45JDG1N1E0. 71 See Alarez, supra note 29. 72 See Leroy & Fariello, supra note 3, at 15. The nuance is subtle yet important, and it has been overlooked by many observers. For an example of the confusion, see Dionne Searcey & David Crawford, World Bank Punishes Units of Alstom SA for Bribery, Wall St. J. (Feb. 23, 2012), avail- able at http://online.wsj.com/article/SB10001424052970203918304577238943984834040 .html; and Greg McArthur, Meet the World Bank’s Anti-bribery Cop, The Globe and Mail (Feb. 7, 2012), available at http://m.theglobeandmail.com/report-on-business/industry -news/the-law-page/meet-the-world-banks-anti-bribery-cop/article2330154/?service=mobile. Notwithstanding the Bank’s desire to rehabilitate vendors, the Bank recognizes its role in http://online.wsj.com/article/SB10001424052970203918304577238943984834040.html http://online.wsj.com/article/SB10001424052970203918304577238943984834040.html http://m.theglobeandmail.com/report-on-business/industry-news/the-law-page/meet-the-world-banks-anti-bribery-cop/article2330154/?service=mobile.Notwithstanding http://go.worldbank.org/45JDG1N1E0 http://m.theglobeandmail.com/report-on-business/industry-news/the-law-page/meet-the-world-banks-anti-bribery-cop/article2330154/?service=mobile.Notwithstanding http://m.theglobeandmail.com/report-on-business/industry-news/the-law-page/meet-the-world-banks-anti-bribery-cop/article2330154/?service=mobile.Notwithstanding The World Bank Legal Review114 release”: in other words, the sanctioned party will be excluded from the pos- sibility of participating in Bank-financed projects for a period of time, and, on condition of proper implementation of appropriate compliance measures, al- lowed to bid once more.73 Operating—as one would expect from bankers—on the understanding that corruption taints the market but that the free market is generally good for all involved, the aim is one of release from debarment and reintegration within the Bank’s (otherwise open) bidding system. Com- pliance with such measures, as well as the system’s objective of rehabilitation and reintroduction, is facilitated through the guidance offered by the integ- rity compliance officer (ICO), whose office also monitors and decides whether conditions have been satisfied.74 The Bank, as much as any other organization, strives toward good gover- nance—that is, the process of effectively addressing shared problems through group decision making.75 Good governance comes only through good rapport and good communication between those governing and those who are gov- erned.76 Critical to such a process are the principles of both transparency and accountability.77 Transparency, which is premised on free access to information, guards against the particular problems of capture and conflicts of interest.78 supporting the rule of law; to this end, if INT substantiates findings of fraud or corruption, the Bank will refer cases to national authorities for prosecution. See, for example, Referrals Made to Governments in FY 10–11, Integrity Vice Presidency Annual Report, Fiscal 2011 44 (World Bank INT 2011), available at http://go.worldbank.org/T40HHT3RF0; see also FAQs, Fraud & Corruption, World Bank, at http://go.worldbank.org/JF938Z5CU0. 73 See Leroy & Fariello, supra note 3, at 14–17. 74 Similarly, the integrity compliance officer (ICO) decides whether conditions established by the sanctions board or EO as part of a conditional nondebarment sanction have been satis- fied. The conditions imposed are likely to be similar to those imposed under debarment with conditional release, including, for example, adoption or improvement of an integrity compliance program and/or other remedial actions related to the relevant misconduct. See Sanctions Procedures, supra note 4, at Article 9.03 (Compliance with Conditions for Non- debarment and Release from Debarment). The ICO was created in 2010. See INT, Sanctions and Compliance, at http://go.worldbank.org/G9UW6Y0DC0. 75 See, for example, Wesley Carrington, Jim DeBuse, & Hee Jin Lee, The Theory of Governance & Accountability (U. of Iowa Center for International Finance and Development 2008). 76 Huma Haider, Claire Mcloughlin, & Zoë Scott, Topic Guide on Communication and Governance (CommGAP & GSDRC 2011), available at http://go.worldbank.org/7BUHFCCQ70. 77 See, for example, Carrington, DeBuse, & Lee, supra note 75; Haider, Mcloughlin, & Scott, su- pra note 76. See also Caroline Freund & Mélise Jaud, Democratic Transitions: Successful, Grad- ual, and Failed, in Accountability and Transparency, World Bank Economists’ Forum 2012 (May 9, 2012); Ryan Booth, Deon Filmer, & Jamele Rigolini, Does Electoral Competition Raise Account- ability?, in Accountability and Transparency, World Bank Economists’ Forum 2012 (May 9, 2012); Marco Larizza, Ryan Jabonski, & Audrey Sacks, Electoral Competition and Access to Information on Public Service Provision: Evidence from Sierra Leone, in Accountability and Transparency, World Bank Economists’ Forum 2012 (May 9, 2012); Carolin Geginat, Adrian Gonzalez, & Valentina Saltaine, Access to Information in Business Regulation, in Accountability and Transparency, World Bank Economists’ Forum 2012 (May 9, 2012). 78 “Capture” refers to the manipulation of policy formation and/or to the distortion of the rule- making process that results in substantial individual gain to the detriment of society or the nation at large; a classic example comes from the profits that accrue to oligarchs of resource- rich countries rather than to the countries and to their citizens. In this context, a “conflict of http://go.worldbank.org/T40HHT3RF0 http://go.worldbank.org/JF938Z5CU0 http://go.worldbank.org/G9UW6Y0DC0 http://go.worldbank.org/7BUHFCCQ70 Transforming through Transparency 115 Accountability, which contemplates the relationship between the organization and its stakeholders, ensures that the organization remains attentive to the needs and interests of its stakeholders and holds managers responsible for deviations thereof.79 However, accountability can operate only in a transpar- ent environment.80 The World Bank Group as a whole has committed itself to furthering the objectives of good governance, transparency, and accountability.81 Notably, the World Bank Group has decided that its internal documents should be made available to the public: adopted at a World Bank Group–wide level under the 2010 Access to Information Policy, all information not on a list of exceptions is disclosed to the public (rather than only information corresponding to a positive list).82 The sanctions system was construed as an exception to the open informa- tion norm and thus stands apart: understanding that the nature of information concerning the sanctions system is fundamentally different from information generally in the Bank’s possession, and recognizing the need to assure the objectiveness of the deliberative process apart from the potential disruptive effect of media attention, the Bank walled off the sanctions system.83 Thus, in short, the general presumptions underlying the Access to Information Policy do not apply to the sanctions regime. Notwithstanding the exception that was carved out for the sanctions pro- cess, it is undesirable if not untenable to maintain the system behind a veil of interest” occurs where there is self-interest competing with a communal interest. See Ro- berta S. Karmel & Claire R. Kelly, The Hardening of Soft Law in Securities Regulation, 34 Brook. J. Intl. L. 883, 946 (2009). See also Geginat, Gonzalez, & Saltaine, supra note 77; Joel Hell- man & Daniel Kaufmann, Confronting the Challenge of State Capture in Transition Economies, Fin. & Dev. (IMF September 2001), available at http://www.imf.org/external/pubs/ft /fandd/2001/09/hellman.htm. 79 See, for example, Helen Darbishire, Proactive Transparency: The Future of the Right to Infor- mation? CommGAP, World Bank, available at http://go.worldbank.org/7BUHFCCQ70. See also UN DESA DPADM, Transparency and Accountability in the Public Sector in the Arab Region, in Concept Paper 2: Transparency and Accountability in Public Financial Administration, RAB/01/006 (Mar. 2004). For a discussion of the evolution of accountability in public orga- nizations and what the term has come to mean, see B. G. Peters in Restoring Accountability Re- search Studies, Vol. 3: Linkages, Responsibilities and Accountabilities (D. Savoie ed., Public Works and Government Services Canada 2006). 80 Id. 81 In the words of former World Bank president Robert Zoellick, “Accountability and transpar- ency are important pillars of the World Bank’s work.” Inspection Panel, available at http:// www.inspectionpanel.org/. See also Lisa Bhansali, Defining Our Path to the “Rule of Law,” Governance for Development, World Bank (Apr. 17, 2012), available at http://blogs.world bank.org/governance/defining-our-path-to-the-rule-of-law. 82 See The World Bank Policy on Access to Information (Jul. 1, 2010), paragraph 13, available at http://go.worldbank.org/LN06W7ZCB0. See also Disclosure Policy Review & Global Con- sultations, World Bank, available at http://go.worldbank.org/FSBLXEWJ50. 83 One of the categorical exceptions in which most information is kept confidential is “other disclosure regimes,” which includes the Bank’s sanctions regime. http://www.imf.org/external/pubs/ft/fandd/2001/09/hellman.htm http://go.worldbank.org/7BUHFCCQ70 http://blogs.worldbank.org/governance/defining-our-path-to-the-rule-of-law http://go.worldbank.org/LN06W7ZCB0 http://go.worldbank.org/FSBLXEWJ50 http://www.imf.org/external/pubs/ft/fandd/2001/09/hellman.htm http://www.inspectionpanel.org/ http://www.inspectionpanel.org/ http://blogs.worldbank.org/governance/defining-our-path-to-the-rule-of-law The World Bank Legal Review116 secrecy;84 therefore, the regime’s actors have worked steadily toward the goal of ever-greater transparency. A series of events in 2011 is particularly reveal- ing. In January 2011, the first notable step to enhance transparency was taken with the updating and making public of the Bank’s Sanctioning Guidelines.85 These guidelines, which attempt to balance predictability with sufficient and equitable flexibility, afford clarity about the imposition of sanctions and offer guidance to INT in its negotiation of settlements.86 In November 2011, the Bank released, for the first time, a detailed information note describing the entire sanctions regime.87 This note gives the public an understanding of the sys- tem as a whole, making public the system’s internal relations and operations, information that was previously largely unknowable to outsiders. An even bigger step came in December 2011, when the Bank published both the undis- puted first-tier determinations (that is, those of the EO),88 and, in decisions that are fully reasoned and include relevant facts and the applied legal reasoning,89 the decisions of the system’s appellate body (that is, those of the Sanctions Board).90 These developments evince the Bank’s commitment to making fair- ness, transparency, and accountability key tenets of the World Bank Group’s sanctions reform agenda91—indeed, the Bank continually explores ways to further transparency and accountability. It should be cautioned that, although the actors of the sanctions system are seeking to make the system more open, total disclosure is not contemplated. For instance, disclosure is limited to undisputed EO determinations and to Sanctions Board decisions, not to all documents or products of the system. Thus, for the sake of the deliberative process, confidentiality is maintained throughout the process, with disclosure of undisputed determinations and decisions made only when they are final. Similarly, INT maintains a “positive list” approach that is intended to cover information that could “be harmful to innocent persons; undermine the work of these groups; or could interfere with 84 Such notions are in keeping with general notions of due process, for example, Article 6, Section 1, of the European Convention on Human Rights (“In the determination of his civil rights and obligations or of any criminal charge against him, everyone is entitled to a fair and public hearing within a reasonable time by an independent and impartial tribunal estab- lished by law. Judgment shall be pronounced publicly”). 85 World Bank Group Sanctioning Guidelines (Jan. 1, 2011), Key and Reference Documents, World Bank, available at http://go.worldbank.org/CVUUIS7HZ0. 86 Sanctions Regime—The 2008–2010 Reforms, World Bank, available at http://go.worldbank .org/P7Z3PKTXP0. See also Leroy & Fariello, supra note 3, at 19. 87 The World Bank Group’s Sanctions Regime: Information Note, available at http:// go.worldbank.org/CVUUIS7HZ0. 88 See Sanctions Procedures, supra note 4, at Article 10.01(b); Evaluation and Suspension Officer Determinations in Uncontested Proceedings, World Bank, available at http://go.worldbank .org/G7EO0UXW90. 89 Sanctions Board Law Digest, World Bank, available at http://go.worldbank.org/S9PFFM D6X0. 90 Id. 91 See, for example, Notes from the Sanctions Board Chair, in Sanctions Board Law Digest, supra note 89. http://go.worldbank.org/CVUUIS7HZ0 http://go.worldbank.org/P7Z3PKTXP0 http://go.worldbank.org/P7Z3PKTXP0 http://go.worldbank.org/G7EO0UXW90 http://go.worldbank.org/S9PFFMD6X0 http://go.worldbank.org/CVUUIS7HZ0 http://go.worldbank.org/CVUUIS7HZ0 http://go.worldbank.org/G7EO0UXW90 http://go.worldbank.org/S9PFFMD6X0 Transforming through Transparency 117 the work of the groups that play an independent role within the institution.”92 Thus, although the actors have taken the initiative of making the sanctions system as accessible as possible, the entirety of the process is not made public. In effect, the result of this transparency is an increase in both empower- ment and confidence for stakeholders and external participants. Publication of the Sanctions Board Law Digest is an excellent illustration: the Digest fosters greater access to and awareness of the public while resulting in greater cer- tainty and deterrence due to the regime’s heightened visibility.93 At the same time, the Digest offers illustrations of the legal principles at play and how they are to be applied.94 The transparency resulting from offering to the public the decision-making process—the logic, its application, and the context for judg- ment—serves as a mechanism for accountability for all the various actors in the system. Instruments like the Digest also enforce the notion of indepen- dence, a notion central to a properly functioning dispute-resolution system.95 On the flip side, appeals for abuse of discretion keep both Bank Management and the ICO (who monitors implementation of the compliance systems) ac- countable. As a result, stakeholders have not only reason to be confident in the Bank and in its actors but also the tools necessary for ensuring continued high standards of quality, and Bank adherence to those standards and to the rules that shape them. 92 See INT, The Disclosure of Information Policy of the Integrity Vice Presidency (Feb. 3, 2011), avail- able at http://go.worldbank.org/J65IMLGAX0. The positive list is limited to (1) redacted fi- nal investigation reports (FIRs) that set out findings and recommendations at the conclusion of INT’s external investigations and may be followed by sanctions proceedings; (2) redacted Detailed Implementation Review reports (DIRs) of integrity risks in WBG-financed projects, and assessments of measures designed to prevent them; (3) INT’s annual report; (4) reports and other information generated as part of INT’s preventive efforts, for example, thematic reviews, “lessons learned” publications, training, and capacity-building materials; (5) policy papers; and list of debarred companies. 93 See President’s Introduction, in Sanctions Board Law Digest, supra note 89 (“Sanctions pro- tect Bank Group funds and member countries’ development projects by excluding proven wrongdoers from our operations and financing. Sanctions also deter other participants or potential bidders in Bank Group–financed operations from engaging in fraud, collusion, or corruption. By holding companies and individuals accountable through a fair and robust process, the Bank Group’s sanctions system promotes integrity and levels the playing field for those committed to clean business practices”). 94 See Notes from the Sanctions Board Chair, in Sanctions Board Law Digest, supra note 89. 95 In both common and civil law traditions, emphasis is placed on rule of law principles, no- tably that of separation of powers and its incumbent notion of judicial independence. The notion of separation of powers was first discussed by Locke, Second Treatise on Government chapter XII, section 143 (1690). However, Montesquieu is the best-known theorist who has treated the topic. Montesquieu, L’esprit des lois vol. 1, book XI, chapter 6, page 219 (1749). Because the judiciary is generally understood as the “weakest” branch of government, it is widely accepted that it must have the most substantial structural independence from undue influence. In the words of US Supreme Court chief justice Marshall, “The greatest scourge an angry Heaven ever inflicted upon an ungrateful and a sinning people, was an ignorant, a corrupt, or a dependent judiciary.” Quoted in John B. Cassoday, John Scott, & John Marshall, The American Lawyer vol. VII, 60 (Stumpf & Steurer 1899). http://go.worldbank.org/J65IMLGAX0 The World Bank Legal Review118 The move toward transparency is good practice and is in keeping with general rule of law dictates.96 Moreover, it is hoped that such confidence will further encourage worldwide participation in the combat against fraud and corruption and in the development of law and justice. Opening up the sanc- tions system demonstrates both to those “in the docket” as respondents and to external observers that the Bank has a robust and deliberative sanctions system. This kind of a system inspires trust and confidence, thereby encourag- ing engagement with the Bank at all levels, be it at the level of the sanctions process or in deciding whether to do business with the Bank. Conclusion Poverty persists and economies stagnate or fail when innovation and growth lag.97 Law and justice offer the infrastructure to nurture the trust and certainty that in turn promote innovation and growth.98 However, economic growth should not be considered a panacea for social problems, nor should the ben- efits of providing law and justice be understood as merely the handmaid of economic growth.99 Just law encourages social cohesion, equality, citizen em- powerment, and justice—“[a]fter all, the law is, or ought to be, but the hand- maid of justice”100 and “an unjust law is no law at all.”101 More sophisticated and more formal legal systems expand economic opportunities by creating trust among strangers and expectations of generalized reciprocity,102 therein encouraging the building of communities of hope, trust, and prosperity. De- velopment, therefore, cannot be read as advancing economic development in the strictest sense of the term; a sense of ownership and empowerment must also be nurtured. Accordingly, more attention must be paid to strengthening governance. To achieve such an end, legal and governance institutions must be developed, and a sense of the importance of the rule of law must be fos- tered.103 However, such development can occur only if stakeholders believe 96 “The rule of law can be defined as a system in which the laws are public knowledge, are clear in meaning, and apply equally to everyone.” Thomas Carothers, The Rule of Law Revival, 77 Foreign Affairs 96 (1998). 97 Cooter & Schafer, supra note 28, at 5. See also Niall Ferguson, Civilization: The West and the Rest (Penguin 2011). 98 Cooter & Schafer, supra note 28, at 1–26. See also Ferguson, supra note 97; Daron Acemoglu & James A. Robinson, Why Nations Fail: The Origins of Power, Prosperity, and Poverty (Random House 2012). 99 See Carothers, supra note 96, at 95–105. See also Philip Alston, The Myopia of the Handmaidens: International Lawyers and Globalization, 3 Euro. J. Intl. L. 423–48 (1997); Shirley V. Scott, Inter- national Lawyers: Handmaidens, Chefs, or Birth Attendants? A Response to Philip Alston, 9 Euro. J. Intl. L. 750 –56 (1998). See also Jim Yong Kim et al. ed., Dying for Growth: Global Inequality and the Health of the Poor 7, 3 (Common Courage Press 2000). 100 Lord Penzance, Combe v. Edwards (1878), L. Reports 3 P.D. 142. 101 St. Augustine of Hippo. 102 Cooter & Schafer, supra note 28, at 82 et seq. 103 See, for example, Lisa Bhansali, Defining Our Path to the “Rule of Law,” Governance for Devel- Transforming through Transparency 119 that the systems are accountable, which in turn requires transparency. Lead- ing by example, the World Bank is adhering to social accountability by mak- ing its sanctions regime increasingly transparent and robust. Internationally, the Bank plays an active role104 in combating the “cancer of corruption.”105 However, for enduring change to occur there must be not only outside support but also the will to reform; that will can come only from with- in the community.106 Merely enacting good laws does little without substantial investment and corresponding changes in implementation and enforcement that nurture mutual trust.107 Realizing as much from its extensive experience in rule of law and justice reform projects,108 the Bank emphasizes transparency and accountability across its work, and in its own sanctions regime in particu- lar, is intended to create a sense of trust, confidence, and ownership, that (it is hoped) will elicit that ever-so-essential will for change. The Bank has further bolstered transparency’s transformative effect by crafting an innovative sui generis system that allows it to attentively and opment, World Bank (Apr. 17, 2012), available at http://blogs.worldbank.org/governance /defining-our-path-to-the-rule-of-law. 104 In taking up this area, the Bank has overcome the strictest interpretations of the “political prohibition” that bars it from interfering in the political affairs of its members. The IBRD Ar- ticles of Agreement contain a provision that states that “[t]he Bank and its officers shall not interfere in the political affairs of any member; nor shall they be influenced in their decisions by the political character of the member or members concerned.” See IBRD Articles of Agree- ment, Article IV, Section 10. IDA Articles of Agreement contain an identical provision. See IDA Articles of Agreement, Article V, Section 6. Almost-identical provisions are contained in the Agreement Establishing the Inter-American Development Bank, Article VIII, Section 5(f); the Articles of Agreement of the Asian Development Bank, Chapter VI, Article 36; and the Agreement Establishing the African Development Bank, Chapter V, Article 38. In contrast, the constituent documents of EBRD and EIB do not contain any such restriction. See also Hassane Cissé, Should the “Political Prohibition” in Charters of International Financial Institu- tions Be Revisited? The Case of the World Bank, in International Financial Institutions and Global Legal Governance (Hassane Cissé, Daniel D. Bradlow, & Benedict Kingsbury ed., World Bank 2011). 105 Wolfensohn, supra note 6, at 50. See also Transparency International USA, World Bank– Siemens Agreement Sends Strong Signal ( Jul. 2, 2009), available at http://www.transparency -usa.org/news/documents/TIUSASiemensRelease7.2.09.pdf. For example, the Bank is keenly engaging with national authorities. See, for example, News & Broadcast, World Bank, World Bank Welcomes Norwegian Convictions of Three Former Employees of Norwegian Company “Norconsult” in Bribery Case in Tanzania, Press Release No. 2012/029/INT ( Jul. 22, 2011), available at http://go.worldbank.org/VO2EW48OO0. 106 See Carothers, supra note 96, at 96. 107 Id., at 104. 108 Compare, for example, the great increase in projects over the course of the years: Initia- tives in Legal and Judicial Reform 2002 (World Bank 2002) (listing 330 Bank-financed projects related to legal and judicial reform, including a US$58 million loan to Russia), available at http://go.worldbank.org/PJHSQT4RA0; Initiatives in Legal and Judicial Reform 2004 (World Bank 2004) (approximating the number of Bank-financed projects related to legal and judi- cial reform at 600), available at http://go.worldbank.org/PJHSQT4RA0; Initiatives in Justice Reform 2009 (World Bank 2009) (noting that the Bank’s current justice sector assistance and reform portfolio comprises nearly 2,500 justice reform activities in developing or transition countries), available at http://go.worldbank.org/PJHSQT4RA0. http://blogs.worldbank.org/governance/defining-our-path-to-the-rule-of-law http://www.transparency-usa.org/news/documents/TIUSASiemensRelease7.2.09.pdf http://go.worldbank.org/PJHSQT4RA0 http://go.worldbank.org/PJHSQT4RA0 http://go.worldbank.org/PJHSQT4RA0 http://www.transparency-usa.org/news/documents/TIUSASiemensRelease7.2.09.pdf http://go.worldbank.org/VO2EW48OO0 http://blogs.worldbank.org/governance/defining-our-path-to-the-rule-of-law The World Bank Legal Review120 expeditiously engage respondents of all shapes and sizes. Until recently, those borrowing from the Bank had their freedom restricted: not only did borrowers not understand the nature of the Bank’s debarment system; they also had lim- ited decision-making powers as the Bank decided on whether certain contrac- tors were employable. The opening up of the Bank’s sanctions regime gives increased confidence to borrowers and contractors alike, as they can see the robust and deliberative nature of the Bank’s system; this opening up also will make the sanctions system more predictable and accessible. Of course, the sanctions system—as with any judicial recourse—remains a contingency: it is the unhappy alternative, not the desired route. That said, confidence in the system is of enduring importance to bolstering the rule of law, as obscuring the nature of that system can have a chilling effect: for those entities doing business with the Bank, not knowing the basis on which the Bank debarred, and yet remaining subject to the possibility of a public shaming, detracted from the Bank’s legitimacy, as well as adding a degree of uncertainty and hassle to working with the Bank. Opening up the sanctions system builds confidence in that system, empowers stakeholders, and has the correlative benefit of building confidence in doing business with the Bank. In matters of governance and of rule of law, the Bank is practicing what it preaches, thereby assuring stakeholders that, in doing business with the Bank, they are not throwing caution to the wind. Such relations improve the political economy of Bank-financed development projects. * * * Left unchecked, fraud and corruption have broad, corrosive, and lingering effects on countries and on communities; they undermine the effectiveness of development projects and erode confidence in systems and in societies.109 The consequence of unchecked corruption is an increase in corruption, as well as a general lack of public confidence in democratic processes, slowed eco- nomic growth, the deepening of inequality, and a general breakdown in social norms of sensitivity.110 Shoring up the rule of law helps temper corruption and crime.111 The Bank’s sanctions regime plays a key role in combating fraud and 109 See Governance and Anticorruption (GAC) Implementation Plan, OPCS, World Bank (Sep. 28, 2007), available at http://go.worldbank.org/ZFUWCFJQ80; FAQs, Fraud & Cor- ruption, World Bank, at http://go.worldbank.org/JF938Z5CU0. See also Wolfensohn, supra note 6, at 50; Yikona et al., supra note 5; Chaikin & Sharman, supra note 5; Jayasuriya, supra note 5, at 46–58. 110 Id. For instance, the growth of corruption in South Africa resulted in citizens not knowing how to report corruption and, even more alarmingly, in the general belief that reporting would not be beneficial and fear of the consequences of reporting. See Hennie van Vuuren, Small Bribes, Big Challenges: Extent and Nature of Petty Corruption in South Africa, 9 S. Afr. Crime Quarterly (2004). In an interesting though counterintuitive and somewhat question- able conceptualization, Cooter & Schafer argue that certain corruption can serve a beneficial purpose insofar as it subverts laws that impede economic growth; unfortunately, no con- sideration is made of the subversive rule of law effects of this “good” corruption. Cooter & Schafer, supra note 28, at 168–72. 111 See Carothers, supra note 96, at 99. http://go.worldbank.org/ZFUWCFJQ80 http://go.worldbank.org/JF938Z5CU0 Transforming through Transparency 121 corruption around the world, and it is hoped that the opening up of the pro- cess to stakeholders will help to combat corruption further. The international community has recognized that “[c]ommunity devel- opment draws on existing human and material resources in the community to enhance self-help and social support, and to develop flexible systems for strengthening public participation. . . . This requires full and continuous ac- cess to information, learning opportunities . . . , as well as funding support.”112 By developing an effective and innovative sanctions system, and in making that system transparent, the Bank is stepping up its efforts to fight fraud and corruption, with the ultimate goal of strengthening and empowering com- munities. The World Bank’s dream is of a world without poverty; impoverish- ment, however, can come in many forms, and, so the Bank—and the actors in its sanctions regime—is expanding the battlefront. 112 The Ottawa Charter for Health Promotion (Nov. 21, 1986). 123 Human Rights and Development Regime Interaction and the Fragmentation of International Law Siobhán Mcinerney-Lankford Human rights and development interact in a range of ways, and so too do the legal and policy frameworks, or regimes, that govern each.1 In this chapter, “regimes” are defined as “sets of norms, decision-making procedures, and or- ganizations coalescing around functional issue-areas.”2 This chapter considers the connections between human rights and development from the perspective of public international law as “regime interaction,” focusing specifically on the links between human rights law and development policy. It departs from the premise of the centrality of law as a defining feature of human rights3 and legal accountability as a key contribution of human rights and development.4 It espouses the view that more attention is due to human rights law and hu- man rights obligations in the context of development.5 From this the chapter considers the degree to which human rights are integrated explicitly into de- velopment policies and programs and the extent to which human rights are recognized as law in those contexts.6 The views expressed in this article are those of the author and do not necessarily reflect the views of the Board of Executive Directors of the World Bank or the governments they represent. The author thanks Mac Darrow, Olufemi Elias, Nathan Lankford, Victor Mosoti, Hans-Otto Sano, Andres Rigo Sureda, and Chantal Thomas for comments on earlier drafts of this article, and Behnaz Bonyadian, Christian Jimenez-Tomas, and Laura Lalime-Mowry for research assistance. Responsibility for errors or omissions remains with the author. 1 M. Young, Regime Interaction in International Law: Facing Fragmentation (Cambridge U. Press 2012). 2 M. Young, Introduction, in Young, id., at 9. The term is understood to cover both the for- mal or binding legal frameworks governing a particular area or issue, including treaties, norms, legislation, rules, and regulations, and softer measures such as policies, statements, programs, processes, and directives. Nevertheless, the term “regime” is a nonlegal term with no fixed definition that has generated a vast body of literature in both international relations and public international law. See, for example, S. Krasner ed., International Relations (Cornell U. Press 1983). 3 D. Forsythe, Human Rights Studies: On the Dangers of Legalistic Assumptions, in Methods of Hu- man Rights Research (F. Coomans, F. Grünfeld, & M. Kamminga ed., Intersentia 2009). Despite the author’s thesis and cautions, he acknowledges that “law has remained central to the notion of human rights. That is because, . . . it is law that authoritatively defines a society’s understanding of what are human rights at a given point in time.” 4 See S. McInerney-Lankford, Human Rights and Development: A Comment on Challenges and Op- portunities from a Legal Perspective, 1(1) J. of Human Rights Practice 74–75 (2009). 5 For a critical view of the value of international human rights treaties, see O. Hathaway, Do Human Rights Treaties Make a Difference? 111 Yale L. J. 1935–2042 (2002). 6 This chapter considers the potential influence of human rights on development, rather than The World Bank Legal Review124 In particular, this chapter explores the place of international human rights obligations and human rights treaties in development policies and assesses the impact of this role in operational terms.7 It notes that, despite growing recognition of human rights as the subject of binding international law obliga- tions on the part of development agencies and banks, and despite increased emphasis on policy coherence, the trend across development is far from uni- form and in many respects is inconsistent and divergent.8 The chapter argues that the relationship between human rights and development policy can be analyzed as regime interaction. This interaction exemplifies the fragmentation of international law, most evident in the uneven integration of human rights law obligations into development policies and processes. This chapter contends that the growing recognition of human rights in legal and operational terms could advance international policy coherence and mediate risk. It also suggests that the ability of international development in- stitutions and their regimes to adapt to evolving international norms could be expanded to human rights.9 It argues for the place and relevance of hu- man rights in development regimes rather than suggesting particular ways in which potential norm conflicts between the regimes should be resolved. It therefore invites consideration of the relationship of human rights and devel- opment in terms of regime interaction and suggests a frame for future consid- eration of norm interaction. The Relationship of Human Rights and Development Human rights and development connect in a range of ways. The following discussion does not review in detail the conceptual discussions developed elsewhere but rather sets the context for the ensuing discussion of how human rights are reflected in development policy frameworks or regimes to facilitate a discussion of how those regimes interact and the place of legal obligations within that relationship. Human rights and development are different: achieving a positive result in a given field, such as health, is not the same as realizing the right to health; nor will such a result “automatically promote respect for the corresponding right and imbue the rights-holder and duty-bearers with a long-term guaran- tee [or] set of structural claims.”10 Yet, at some intuitive level, human rights the reverse, although it assumes the two-way nature of the relationship between the two. See World Bank, Development and Human Rights: The Role of the World Bank (World Bank 1998). 7 This approach departs from the view that “when we speak of universal human rights, it is international law that defines them in a positivistic sense, for better or worse.” Forsythe, supra note 2, at 61. 8 P. Uvin, Human Rights and Development 47 (Kumarian Press 2004). 9 A. Rigo Sureda, The Law Applicable to the Activities of International Development Banks, in Re- ceuil des cours 217 (Martinus Nijhoff 2005). 10 Anand Grover, Report of the Special Rapporteur on the Right of Everyone to the Enjoyment of the Highest Attainable Standard of Physical and Mental Health, A/HRC/17/25 (Apr. 12, 2011), Human Rights and Development 125 and development share affinities. In substantive ways, they occupy many of the same sectors or spheres, and in certain types of operations, development bears distinct similarities to human rights. The “normative and institutional pluralism”11 that exists between human rights and development results in overlapping activities and mutual influence among their governing regimes, such that the demarcation between them is sometimes difficult to draw.12 It may even be said that the overlap between the two areas or regimes is increasing and that the range of development poli- cies and activities now affecting areas governed by human rights treaties is growing. Some practitioners have even observed that there has not been an evolution in the thinking on matters related to human rights to correlate with the expansion in the mandate of development institutions.13 Moreover, “complex problems have ramifications in many specialized directions.”14 Attempts at strict demarcations between different regimes or competencies fail to register the complex realities of international human rights and development, giving rise to both an increased potential for con- flicting norms in international law and a “situation of ongoing institutional diversity and pluralism and the day-to-day and relatively mundane occur- rences of overlapping forms and inter-regime activity.”15 This is particular- ly true because development and human rights share consistent goals16 but pursue them differently, and their agendas overlap extensively17 and in mutu- ally reinforcing ways.18 paragraph 50, quoting P. Uvin, Human Rights and Development 52–53 (Kumarian Press 2004). 11 M. Young, Regime Interaction in Creating, Implementing and Enforcing International Law, in Young, supra note 1, at 86. 12 On the overlap of domains of activity and regulatory processes at the international level, see B. Kingsbury, Introduction: Global Administrative Law in the Institutional Practice of Global Regu- latory Governance, in World Bank Legal Review vol. 3 (H. Cissé, D. Bradlow, & B. Kingsbury ed., World Bank 2012). 13 Sureda, supra note 9, at 217. 14 Judge Weeramantry dissenting, Use of Nuclear Weapons in Armed Conflict Advisory Opinion (1999) (I) ICJ Rep. 66. 15 Young, supra note 11, at 85. 16 United Nations Development Programme (UNDP), Human Rights and Human Development, in Human Development Report 2000, sections 19–28 (UNDP 2000). See S. Jahan, Millennium Development Goals and Human Rights (2002), available at http://www.inwent.org/ef-texte /human_rights/jahan.htm. See also Report of the Millennium Project, Investing in Development: A Practical Plan to Achieve the Millennium Development Goals, which characterizes the MDGs as human rights: “[The MDGs] are also basic human rights—the rights of each person on the planet to health, education, shelter, and security as pledged in the Universal Declaration of Human Rights and the UN Millennium Declaration” (page 1), available at http://www .unmillenniumproject.org/reports/fullreport.htm. 17 P. Alston, Ships Passing in the Night: The Current State of the Human Rights and Development Debate Seen through the Lens of the Millennium Development Goals, 27(3) Hum. Rights Q. 758. 18 OHCHR, Frequently Asked Questions on Human Rights Based Approach to Development Coopera- tion (UN 2006), and UNDP, Human Development Report 2003: Millennium Development Goals: A Compact among Nations to end Human Poverty (UNDP 2003). See also J. L. Roy, Implementing the http://www.inwent.org/ef-texte/human_rights/jahan.htm http://www.unmillenniumproject.org/reports/fullreport.htm http://www.inwent.org/ef-texte/human_rights/jahan.htm http://www.unmillenniumproject.org/reports/fullreport.htm The World Bank Legal Review126 Examples of this convergence can be identified in the areas of social protec- tion, education, governance, and health, as well as in thematic terms through activities aimed at the protection of women, indigenous peoples, children, and persons with disabilities. The Millennium Development Goals (MDG) illus- trate the proximity and compatibility of human rights and development, even if they are critiqued for their silence on human rights19 and their failure to ad- dress inequalities and the plight of the most vulnerable.20 At a deeper level, human rights and development may be viewed as con- verging in shared principles such as equality, participation, accountability, transparency, and voice, as well as in attention to vulnerable groups, all of which are principles that have become hallmarks of good development prac- tice.21 Both development and the international human rights frameworks give expression to these principles in different ways that evince a convergence of a more deliberate and strategic sort. However, in general legal and policy terms, the international frameworks governing human rights and development occupy separate spheres governed by distinct regimes. Nowhere is this more apparent than in relation to legal obligations.22 International human rights are the purview of treaty frameworks such as the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR)23 and the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (ICESCR),24 along with a range of other universal instruments and their protocols gov- erning issues such as gender discrimination,25 child rights,26 disabilities,27 Millennium Development Goals: Our Human Rights Obligation, 15(1) Libertas, who opines, “many of the MDGs can be reinforced by the binding human rights obligations of states.” 19 Alston, supra note 17, at 796. See, generally, OHCHR, Claiming the Millennium Development Goals: A Human Rights Approach (United Nations 2008), available at http://www2.ohchr .org/SPdocs/Claiming_MDGs_en.pdf. 20 See, for example, M. Langford, A Poverty of Rights: Six Ways to Fix the MDGs, 41(1) IDS Bul- letin 87 ( Jan. 2010). 21 S. McInerney-Lankford & H.-O. Sano, Human Rights Indicators in Development: An Introduc- tion 31– 36 (World Bank 2010). 22 Id., at 36–40. 23 International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR), UN GA Res. 2200A (XXI), 21 UN GAOR Supp. No. 16, at 52, UN Doc. A/6316 (1966), 999 UNTS 171 (entered into force Mar. 23, 1976). 24 International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (ICESCR), UN GA Res. 2200A (XXI), 21 UN GAOR Supp. No. 16, at 49, UN Doc. A/6316 (1966), 993 UNTS 3 (entered into force Jan. 3, 1976). 25 Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination Against Women (CEDAW), UN Doc. A/34/46, at 193 (1979), 1249 UNTS 14 (entered into force Sep. 3, 1981). 26 Convention on the Rights of the Child (CRC), UNTS 3, 28 I.L.M. 1456 (entered into force Sep. 2, 1990). 27 Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities (ICRPD), A/RES/61/106 (adopted Jan. 24, 2007). http://www2.ohchr.org/SPdocs/Claiming_MDGs_en.pdf http://www2.ohchr.org/SPdocs/Claiming_MDGs_en.pdf Human Rights and Development 127 torture,28 and migrant workers.29 This is complemented by regional human rights law frameworks and monitoring systems in Europe (ECHR,30 the Char- ter of Fundamental Rights of the EU31), the Americas,32 and Africa.33 Development, for its part, is defined more by broad-based goals such as the MDGs and general statements, strategies, programs, and policy frame- works of development institutions, which do not generally incorporate inter- national legal norms34 directly or explicitly. Philip Alston has noted the resis- tance to human rights in the context of the MDGs, attributing it to the fact that human rights are “a quintessentially legal domain and thus not one which is suitable for use in a general development studies context.”35 Thus, the binding legal frame of development cooperation tends to operate either at the level of the constitutive instruments of development agencies or at the transactional level of individual legal agreements underpinning particular operations. Al- though each of these instruments is an international agreement36 subject to public international law,37 the bulk of the development policy framework is not the domain of international legal norms, is not usually framed in terms of treaties, and does not readily admit a place for treaty obligations such as those flowing from human rights treaties. Moreover, despite the more recent emphasis on accountability in develop- ment frameworks,38 these frameworks do not involve legal accountability of 28 Convention Against Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punish- ment (CAT ) (Dec. 10, 1984), 1465 UNTS 85 (entered into force Jun. 26, 1987). 29 International Convention on the Protection of the Rights of All Migrant Workers and Mem- bers of Their Families, CPRMW (Dec. 18, 1990), UN GA Res. 45/158 (annex), 30 I.L.M. 1521 (1991) (entered into force Jul. 1, 2003). 30 See http://www.hri.org/docs/ECHR50.html. 31 Official Journal of the European Union C 83/389, available at http://eurlex.europa.eu/Lex UriServ/LexUriServ.do?uri=OJ:C:2010:083:0389:0403:en:PDF. 32 American Convention on Human Rights (Pact of San Jose), OAS Treaty Series No. 36, 1144 UNTS 123 (entered into force Jul. 18, 1978), available at http://www.oas.org/juridico/en glish/treaties/b-32.html. 33 African Charter on Human and Peoples’ Rights, OAU Doc. CAB/LEG/67/3 rev. 5, 21 I.L.M. 58 (1982) (entered into force Oct. 21, 1986). 34 By norms, this chapter refers to legally binding rules that create rights and obligations be- tween subjects of international law. 35 P. Alston, What’s in a Name: Does It Really Matter if Development Policies Refer to Goals, Ideals or Human Rights? 22 SIM Special 101 (1997). 36 Because these international agreements are entered into by UN members, the agreements are subject to the registration requirement of Article 102 of the UN Charter. See A. Broches, The- ory and Practice of Treaty Registration with Particular Reference to Agreements of the International Bank, in Selected Essays World Bank, ICSID, and Other Subjects of Public and Private International Law 99 (Martinus Nijhoff 1995). All treaties and international agreements registered with the United Nations are available at http://treaties.un.org/. 37 I. Shihata, The World Bank Legal Papers 151 (Martinus Nijhoff 2000), in discussing the World Bank general conditions, confirms that the Bank’s loan and guarantee agreements are international agreements that, although insulated from domestic law, are subject to public international law. 38 For example, Global Monitoring is a monitoring framework focused on “how the world is http://eurlex.europa.eu/LexUriServ/LexUriServ.do?uri=OJ:C:2010:083:0389:0403:en:PDF http://www.oas.org/juridico/english/treaties/b-32.html http://www.hri.org/docs/ECHR50.html http://eurlex.europa.eu/LexUriServ/LexUriServ.do?uri=OJ:C:2010:083:0389:0403:en:PDF http://www.oas.org/juridico/english/treaties/b-32.html http://treaties.un.org/ The World Bank Legal Review128 the sort associated with treaties such as human rights treaties, and arguably cannot therefore empower poor or marginalized groups to claim their rights in the development process and bridge the gap between global standards and local circumstances.39 Indeed, some people have argued that accountability itself cannot be separated from contests over the realization of rights and the distribution of resources.40 In general terms, therefore, human rights and development are governed by distinct regimes, including separate legal frameworks, that interact only occasionally and in ways that are far from clear. Only very rarely do human rights law obligations, such as those emanating from human rights treaties, receive formal recognition in the development regimes, and even then the operational consequences of such obligations are not always apparent. This chapter draws on the well-known concept of fragmentation of international law to analyze the relationship between human rights and development and the interaction of the legal and policy regimes that govern each.41 The fragmentation of international law is generally understood to refer to the way in which international law is split into “highly ‘specialized boxes’ that claim relative autonomy from each other and from the general law.”42 It is the subject of extensive academic commentary,43 viewed by many as a product of the expansion and diversification of public international law and connected with the proliferation of special regimes. Some view fragmentation as a prob- lem that undermines the general law and the systemic nature of international law,44 while others view it as inevitable, perhaps even capable of strengthening special regimes.45 Some of the literature focuses on the resolution of conflict between the norms of various special regimes,46 whereas other work explores doing in implementing the policies and actions for achieving the MDGs and related devel- opment outcomes. It is a framework for accountability in global development policy.” See http://go.worldbank.org/AECE2VJFU0 . 39 See P. Newell & J. Wheeler, Rights, Resources and the Politics of Accountability (Institute of De- velopment Studies 2006). 40 Id. 41 The putative causes of this fragmentation are discussed in more detail below. 42 ILC Study Group, Conclusions of the Work of the Study Group on the Fragmentation of Interna- tional Law: Difficulties Arising from the Diversification and Expansion of International Law, UN Doc. A/CN.4/L.682 256 (2006). 43 P. M. Dupuy, The Danger of Fragmentation or Unification of the International Legal System and the International Court of Justice, 31 N.Y.U. J. Intl. L. & Pol. 791–807 (1999); J. Pauwleyn, Bridging Fragmentation and Unity: International Law as a Universe of Inter-connected Islands, 25 Mich. J. Intl. L. 903–17 (2004); K. Wellens & R. Vinaixa ed., L’influence des sources sur l’unité et la frag- mentation du droit international (Bruylant 2006). The 105th Meeting of the American Society of International Law addressed some similar themes in Harmony and Dissonance in International Law (2011). 44 M. Koskenniemi & P. Leino, Fragmentation of International Law? Postmodern Anxieties, 15 Leiden J. Intl. L. 553 (2002), discuss a range of views on the various risks of fragmentation. 45 B. Simma, Fragmentation in a Positive Light, 25 Mich. J. Intl. L. 845 (2004). 46 For example, M. Milanović, Norm Conflict in International Law: Whither Human Rights? 20 http://go.worldbank.org/AECE2VJFU0 Human Rights and Development 129 the ways in which norms and institutions from disparate regimes overlap and interact.47 This chapter adopts the latter approach, applying it to the interac- tion of regimes governing human rights and development. Human Rights and Development: Regime Interaction and Policy Coherence What, then, is the nature of the interaction between the regimes governing human rights and development?48 Where and how do the regimes interact at the level of legal and policy discourse? In particular, how are human rights reflected in the development policy frameworks of bilateral and multilateral donors? This section outlines the various levels of formal interaction between the development and human rights regimes in high-level political statements and soft law, as well as the individual policies of particular agencies and insti- tutions. From there, it assesses the nature and quality of the transposition of human rights, whether in general references, as principles, or as legal obliga- tions with direct operational implications. International Political Statements and Soft Law Soft law measures dating from the 1960s link human rights and development. These recognize that failure to reach development goals impedes the realiza- tion of human rights and that “the achievement of lasting progress in the im- plementation of human rights is dependent upon sound and effective national and international policies of economic and social development.”49 Perhaps the most direct attempt at linking human rights and development emerges in the right to development. In 1986, the UN General Assembly adopted the Declara- tion on the Right to Development,50 which pronounces the right to develop- ment as a new human right, one of the so-called third generation of human rights. At the same time these initiatives were under way at the international political level, philosophers such as Amartya Sen and Martha Nussbaum were forging links between human rights and development. Sen’s concept of devel- opment as freedom, under which the essential goal of development is expand- ing substantive human freedoms, or “capabilities,” has a natural affinity with human rights and human rights–based approaches to development, particu- larly in its emphasis on the importance of voice for marginalized groups.51 Duke J. Comp. & Intl. L. 69 (2009). 47 M. Young ed., Regime Interaction in International Law (Cambridge U. Press 2012). 48 For a definition of regimes, see Young, supra note 1. 49 Proclamation of Teheran, Final Act of the International Conference on Human Rights, Tehe- ran, Apr. 22 to May 13, 1968, UN Doc. A/CONF. 32/41, at 3 (1968). 50 Declaration on the Right to Development, A/RES/41/128 (Dec. 4, 1986). See also S. Marks, Emerging Human Rights: A New Generation for the 1980’s, 33 Rutgers L. Rev. 435 (1981); S. Marks, The Human Right to Development: Between Rhetoric and Reality? 17 Harv. Hum. Rights J. 137 (2004). 51 A. Sen, Development as Freedom (Oxford U. Press 2000). The World Bank Legal Review130 The Declaration on the Right to Development underscores the links be- tween human rights and development by “[r]ecognizing that the human per- son is the central subject of the development process and that development policy should therefore make the human being the main participant and ben- eficiary of development.” Article 1 states, “The right to development is an in- alienable human right by virtue of which every human person and all peoples are entitled to participate in, contribute to, and enjoy economic, social, cultural and political development, in which all human rights and fundamental free- doms can be fully realized.” In 1993, the Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action, in addition to reaffirming the right to development, asserted that “[d]emocracy, develop- ment, and respect for human rights and fundamental freedoms are interde- pendent and mutually reinforcing.”52 Although such measures represent efforts to connect human rights and development cohesively, they also underscore the fragmentation of interna- tional law by not being binding and by the fact that they do not connect hu- man rights obligations operationally with development.53 The marginality of the right to development in normative terms and the vagueness surrounding content and meaning in the operational frameworks of development agencies are evidence of the separateness of the human rights and development frame- works rather than an example of their convergence. In 2000, the global community adopted the Millennium Declaration, which contains commitments to respect human rights and uphold the Uni- versal Declaration of Human Rights.54 This was followed by the 2010 Millen- 52 Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action, A/CONF.157/23 ( Jul. 12, 1993; adopted by the World Conference on Human Rights on Jun. 25, 1993), paragraph 8. 53 The discourse around the right to development has often been a polarized one, generat- ing sharp differences between developed and less developed countries in the context of de- mands for redressing economic imbalances and a new international economic order. For a thoughtful review of the history and implications of the right to development, see I. Bunn, The Right to Development: Implications for International Economic Law, 15 Am. U. Intl. L.J. 1425 (2000). On the right to development more generally, see S. Choudhury, The Right to Develop- ment in International Law (Martinus Nijhoff 1992). 54 Section V of the Millennium Declaration, on human rights, democracy, and good gover- nance, reads: 24. We will spare no effort to promote democracy and strengthen the rule of law, as well as respect for all internationally recognized human rights and fundamental freedoms, including the right to development. 25. We resolve therefore: • To respect fully and uphold the Universal Declaration of Human Rights. • To strive for the full protection and promotion in all our countries of civil, political, economic, social and cultural rights for all. • To strengthen the capacity of all our countries to implement the principles and prac- tices of democracy and respect for human rights, including minority rights. • To combat all forms of violence against women and to implement the Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against Women. Human Rights and Development 131 nium Summit Outcome document, Keeping the Promises: United to Achieve the Millennium Development Goals,55 which contains several references to human rights and international law instruments, reaffirming full respect for interna- tional law and principles56 and for all human rights, including the right to development.57 It also notes that gender equality and women’s full enjoyment of human rights are essential to economic and social development, including the achievement of the MDGs.58 Agencies such as the UN Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights (OHCHR) have continued to emphasize the importance of human rights to development as part of a broader agenda of international policy coherence.59 This was affirmed by the UN High Commis- sioner for Human Rights in the context of the right to development: “We must foster policy coherence and systemic integration of human rights, including the right to development, across sectors, across institutions and across layers of governance. Human aspirations for well-being can be realized only when there is a strong accountability framework.”60 In the area of aid effectiveness, although the 2005 Paris Declaration on Aid Effectiveness61 does not contain any explicit reference to human rights as a cross-cutting theme,62 it does confirm five core principles deemed essential to improving the effectiveness of development assistance and contributing to meeting the MDGs: ownership, alignment, harmonization, managing for re- sults, and mutual accountability to improve the quality of aid and its impact on development. In 2008, the Accra Agenda for Action (AAA) proclaimed re- spect for human rights as a cornerstone for achieving enduring impact on the • To take measures to ensure respect for and protection of the human rights of mi- grants, migrant workers and their families, to eliminate the increasing acts of racism and xenophobia in many societies and to promote greater harmony and tolerance in all societies. • To work collectively for more inclusive political processes, allowing genuine partici- pation by all citizens in all our countries. • To ensure the freedom of the media to perform their essential role and the right of the public to have access to information. 55 Integrated and Coordinated Implementation of and Follow-Up to the Outcomes of the Major UN Conferences and Summits in the Economic, Social, and Related Fields. Follow-up to the Outcome of the Millennium Summit, A/65/L.1 (Sep. 17, 2010). 56 Paragraph 2, 2010 Millennium Summit Outcome document. 57 Paragraph 3, 2010 Millennium Summit Outcome document. 58 Paragraph 12, 2010 Millennium Summit Outcome document. 59 See below for a discussion of international policy coherence. 60 Closing Statement by the High Commissioner for Human Rights at UN General Assem- bly Event to Commemorate the 25th Anniversary of the United Nations Declaration on the Right to Development (Nov. 8, 2011), available at http://www.ohchr.org/en/NewsEvents /Pages/DisplayNews.aspx?NewsID=11583&LangID=E. 61 See http://www.oecd.org/dataoecd/11/41/34428351.pdf and http://ec.europa.eu/devel opment/icenter/repository/SEC_PDF_2009_1137_F_ACTE_PCD_EN.pdf (2009). 62 Paragraph 42 of the 2005 Paris Declaration on Aid Effectiveness notes the need for “har- monisation efforts on other cross cutting issues such as gender equality and other thematic issues.” http://www.ohchr.org/en/NewsEvents/Pages/DisplayNews.aspx?NewsID=11583&LangID=E http://www.oecd.org/dataoecd/11/41/34428351.pdf http://ec.europa.eu/development/icenter/repository/SEC_PDF_2009_1137_F_ACTE_PCD_EN.pdf http://www.ohchr.org/en/NewsEvents/Pages/DisplayNews.aspx?NewsID=11583&LangID=E http://ec.europa.eu/development/icenter/repository/SEC_PDF_2009_1137_F_ACTE_PCD_EN.pdf The World Bank Legal Review132 lives and potential of poor women, men, and children, stating that it is “vital that all our policies address these issues in a more systematic and coherent way.”63 In paragraph 13(c), the AAA goes further: “Developing countries and do- nors will ensure that their respective development policies and programmes are designed and implemented in ways consistent with their agreed inter- national commitments on gender equality, human rights, disability and en- vironmental sustainability.” The 2011 outcome document from the Fourth High-Level Forum on Aid Effectiveness in Busan explicitly preserves the commitments of the AAA and, like the AAA, contains provisions on human rights. In addition, it provides for the right to development and confirms that the “common principles which—consistent with our agreed international commitments on human rights, decent work, gender equality, environmental sustainability and disability—form the foundation of our cooperation for ef- fective development.”64 The trend among such high-level statements and declarations is clearly in favor of recognizing human rights more explicitly and in terms of obliga- tions and international commitments. This movement promotes a vision of development and human rights that supports international policy coherence and that recognizes the potential impacts of actions in one policy realm on other areas. At the level of general political statements, therefore, the trend increasingly recognizes the relevance of human rights law obligations to de- velopment cooperation, including aid effectiveness. Development Policies At an institutional level, the policies of many development agencies and banks reflect the points of convergence, albeit in different ways. This section traces the links between human rights and development in these policies, noting the ways in which they approach the question of human rights as the subject of binding international law obligations. References to Human Rights Some policies contain general or preambular references to human rights, but the operational implications of these references remain unclear. Such references might cite the importance of human rights in the development process or in- clude provisions regarding the respect of human rights of particular groups; some even go so far as to define human rights by reference to the relevant international legal instruments. Examples are found in the indigenous peoples 63 Accra Agenda for Action, paragraph 3. 64 Busan Partnership for Effective Development Cooperation, Outcome Document (Dec. 1, 2011), paragraph 11, available at http://www.aideffectiveness.org/busanhlf4/images/stories /hlf4/OUTCOME_DOCUMENT_-_FINAL_EN.pdf. See also references to human rights and rights-based approaches in relation to the Millennium Declaration (paragraph 3) and the role of CSOs (paragraph 22). http://www.aideffectiveness.org/busanhlf4/images/stories/hlf4/OUTCOME_DOCUMENT_-_FINAL_EN.pdf http://www.aideffectiveness.org/busanhlf4/images/stories/hlf4/OUTCOME_DOCUMENT_-_FINAL_EN.pdf Human Rights and Development 133 policies of a number of multilateral development banks, such as the World Bank65 and the Inter-American Development Bank (IDB). The IDB Operational Policy on Indigenous Peoples makes numerous references to indigenous peo- ples’ rights,66 defined as “the rights of indigenous peoples and individuals, whether originating in the indigenous legislation issued by States, in other rel- evant national legislation, in applicable international norms in force for each country, or in the indigenous juridical systems of each people, hereinafter col- lectively referred to as the ‘applicable legal norms.’”67 The policy enumerates the relevant international and regional human rights instruments, also mak- ing reference to the jurisprudence of international human rights bodies.68 Human Rights as General Principles The frameworks of some agencies evidence a more strategic engagement with human rights, acknowledging their importance for development policy and practice69 and highlighting the links between human rights and sustainable 65 Operational Policy on Indigenous Peoples 4.10, the preamble of which reads: “This policy contributes to the Bank’s mission of poverty reduction and sustainable development by en- suring that the development process fully respects the dignity, human rights, economies, and cultures of Indigenous Peoples.” 66 http://idbdocs.iadb.org/wsdocs/getdocument.aspx?docnum=691261. 67 Id., paragraph 1.2. 68 Page 1, footnote 4 , IDB Operational Policy on Indigenous Peoples, reads: [T]hose international norms in force for each country are defined as follows: Interna- tional legislation includes, as in force for each country, the United Nations Universal Declaration of Human Rights (1948), the International Covenant on Civil and Politi- cal Rights (1966), the American Convention on Human Rights (1969), the International Covenant on Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights (1976), the International Conven- tion on the Elimination of all Forms of Racial Discrimination (1966), the Convention on the Rights of the Child (1990), the International Labor Organization (ILO) Convention 107 concerning the Protection and Integration of Indigenous and Other Tribal and Semi- Tribal Populations in Independent Countries (1957), ILO Convention 169 concerning Indigenous and Tribal Populations in Independent Countries (1989), Agenda 21 ad- opted by the United Nations Conference on Environment and Development (UNCED) (1992), and the International Convention on Biological Diversity (1992), as well as the corresponding international jurisprudence of the Inter-American Court of Human Rights or similar bodies whose jurisdiction has been accepted by the relevant coun- try. Other international instruments currently in preparation, such as the draft United Nations Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples and the draft American Dec- laration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples, establish aspirational principles that may be taken into account to the extent that these instruments are finalized and subscribed by the relevant country. The UN Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples was adopted by the UN General Assembly in September 2007. 69 NZAid, Human Rights Policy Statement, 4 (2002), available at http://www.nzaid.govt.nz /library/docs/nzaid-human-rights-policy.pdf; Danish Ministry of Foreign Affairs, Democratisation and Human Rights for the Benefit of the People: Strategic Priorities for Dan- ish Support for Good Governance, page 3 (2009), available at http://www.um.dk/NR /rdonlyres/D04B984F-41A2-4E7E-81C1-A35C09F95964/0/DraftDHRstrategyFINALVER SION030309.pdf. Denmark’s general policy on development, “The Right to a Better Life,” was adopted in 2012. The first of five strands of the strategy is freedom, democracy, and human rights. Available at http://um.dk/en/danida-en/goals/strategy/. http://www.nzaid.govt.nz/library/docs/nzaid-human-rights-policy.pdf http://www.um.dk/NR/rdonlyres/D04B984F-41A2-4E7E-81C1-A35C09F95964/0/DraftDHRstrategyFINALVERSION030309.pdf http://um.dk/en/danida-en/goals/strategy/ http://www.nzaid.govt.nz/library/docs/nzaid-human-rights-policy.pdf http://www.um.dk/NR/rdonlyres/D04B984F-41A2-4E7E-81C1-A35C09F95964/0/DraftDHRstrategyFINALVERSION030309.pdf http://www.um.dk/NR/rdonlyres/D04B984F-41A2-4E7E-81C1-A35C09F95964/0/DraftDHRstrategyFINALVERSION030309.pdf http://idbdocs.iadb.org/wsdocs/getdocument.aspx?docnum=691261 The World Bank Legal Review134 development.70 Others draw connections between the international human rights law framework and the MDGs71 and compliance with human rights principles and improvements in MDG-oriented development.72 Several agen- cies have well-established human rights mainstreaming policies73 or policies founded on a rights perspective.74 Such policies promote the integration of hu- man rights into country programs or existing aid interventions across sectors or promote the rights of certain groups such as children, women, minorities and indigenous peoples, or persons with disabilities. Human Rights–Based Approaches Some governments have adopted human rights–based approaches to develop- ment.75 At the global level, the United Nations is the most prominent example of a general rights-based approach to development,76 founded directly on the legal obligations enshrined in the UN Charter, the Universal Declaration, and 70 Human Rights and Australia’s Aid Program. From an aid perspective, development and hu- man rights are interdependent and mutually reinforcing. For development to be sustainable, individuals in developing countries must have secure and long-term access to the resources required to satisfy their basic needs, be they economic, social, cultural, civil, or political. At the broadest level, therefore, the entire Australian aid program contributes to the realiza- tion of human rights. See http://www.ausaid.gov.au/keyaid/humanrights.cfm. 71 Netherlands Ministry of Foreign Affairs, Human Dignity for All: A Human Rights Strategy for Foreign Policy. There are major similarities between the MDGs and the objectives of the human rights instruments. Both aim to eliminate hunger, improve access to education and health care, and improve the position of women, children, and other vulnerable groups. All the MDGs also have an equivalent in the international human rights instruments, par- ticularly the International Covenant on Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights (ICESCR), the Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination against Women (CEDAW), and the International Convention on the Rights of the Child (CRC). 72 BMZ, Human Rights in German Development Policy, BMZ Strategy Paper 4 (2011), at section 2.3; see also Germany’s Development Policy Action Plan on Human Rights (2008 –10). 73 See, for example, F. Uggla, Mainstreaming at Sida: A Synthesis Report 7, Sida Studies in Evalu- ation No. 5 (2007), available at http://www.oecd.org/dataoecd/0/40/39070485.pdf and http://www.sida.se/English/. 74 Sweden’s policy for democratic development and human rights in Swedish develop- ment cooperation, 2010–14. Memorandum Appendix to Government Decision 2010-01-2 (UF2009/33076/UP). “With this policy, the Government is raising its level of ambition and clarifying its aims concerning Swedish development cooperation in working towards the goal of democratic development and greater respect for human rights in developing countries.” Contrasting a rights-based approach and a rights-based perspective, see L. Munro, The “Human Rights-Based Approach to Programming”: A Contradiction in Terms? in Rights-Based Approaches to Development Exploring the Potential and the Pitfalls 187–206 (S. Hickey & D. Mitlin ed., Kumarian Press 2009). According to Munro, a rights-based approach insists that everything the organiza- tion does be based on human rights, whereas a rights-based perspective is less absolute. 75 For instance, a key aim of Germany’s Development Policy Action Plan on Human Rights (2008 –10) is “systematically integrating a human rights based approach into develop- ment.” Available at http://www.bmz.de/en/service/infothek/fach/konzepte/konzept167 .pdf?follow=adword. 76 See, especially, UNICEF’s rights-based approach to programming, Munro, supra note 74, at 193–202. For a critical review of human rights–based approaches in development, see M. Darrow & A. Tomas, Power, Capture and Conflict: A Call for Human Rights Accountability in Development Cooperation, 27 Hum. Rights Q. 471–538 (2005). http://www.ausaid.gov.au/keyaid/humanrights.cfm http://www.oecd.org/dataoecd/0/40/39070485.pdf http://www.bmz.de/en/service/infothek/fach/konzepte/konzept167.pdf?follow=adword http://www.bmz.de/en/service/infothek/fach/konzepte/konzept167.pdf?follow=adword http://www.sida.se/English/ Human Rights and Development 135 the core UN human rights treaties. The 2003 UN Interagency Common Un- derstanding of a Human Rights–Based Agreement77 was adopted by the UN Development Group (UNDG) to ensure the consistent application of a human rights–based approach by UN agencies, funds, and programs at global and regional levels, especially at the country level in relation to the UN Common Country Assessments/UN Development Assistance Frameworks (CCA /UNDAF), which were established to strengthen the coherence and effective- ness of the UN system’s contribution to countries’ development efforts. The Common Understanding establishes a set of principles that guide and define a human rights approach; it confirms the central importance of the international human rights treaty framework in all development cooperation programs.78 The secretary-general’s 2002 reform program included a decision, known as “Action 2,” to mainstream human rights across country programs.79 Ac- tion 2 was followed by further reform programs in 200580 and backed by the commitment of world leaders at the 2005 UN World Summit81 to mainstream human rights within their national policies and in the development programs of the United Nations. Several UN agencies have led efforts to catalog their experiences and guidance on integrating human rights and rights-based approaches.82 In November 2009, the UNDG established a Human Rights 77 The Human Rights Based Approach to Development Cooperation Towards a Common Understanding Among UN Agencies, available at http://www.undg.org/archive_docs /6959-The_Human_Rights_Based_Approach_to_Development_Cooperation_Towards_a _Common_Understanding_Among_UN.pdf. 78 Those principles are 1. All programmes of development co-operation, policies and technical assistance should further the realisation of human rights as laid down in the Universal Declara- tion of Human Rights and other international human rights instruments. 2. Human rights standards contained in, and principles derived from, the Universal Declaration of Human Rights and other international human rights instruments guide all development cooperation and programming in all sectors and in all phases of the programming process. 3. Development cooperation contributes to the development of the capacity to meet their obligations and/or of “‘rights-holders’’ to claim their rights. 79 Secretary-General, Strengthening of the United Nations: An Agenda for Further Change, A/57/387 (Sep. 9, 2002), from which the strengthening and mainstreaming of human rights in the UN have come to be known as “Action 2.” Action 2, related to strengthening UN support for the promotion and protection of human rights worldwide, was adopted by UNDG, ECHA, and OHCHR in 2003 pursuant to the secretary-general’s report. Its main goal is to develop the capacity of UN humanitarian and development operations to strengthen national human rights promotion and protection systems consistent with international norms and principles. See http://www.un.org/events/action2/. 80 Paragraph 126 contains the commitment to integrate the promotion and protection of human rights into national policies and support the further mainstreaming of human rights through- out the UN system. See also Secretary-General, In Larger Freedom: Towards Security, Develop- ment and Human Rights for All (UN 2005), available at http://www.un.org/largerfreedom/. 81 2005 World Summit Outcome: Resolution adopted by the UN GA A/RES/60/1. 82 UNICEF Guidelines for Human Rights Based Programming Approach CF/EXD/1998-04 (Apr. 21, 1998), available at http://www.fao.org/righttofood/kc/downloads/vl/docs /212951.pdf; UNDP, Human Rights in UNDP: A Practice Note (Apr. 2005), available at http:// http://www.undg.org/archive_docs/6959-The_Human_Rights_Based_Approach_to_Development_Cooperation_Towards_a_Common_Understanding_Among_UN.pdf http://www.un.org/events/action2/ http://www.fao.org/righttofood/kc/downloads/vl/docs/212951.pdf http://www.undg.org/archive_docs/6959-The_Human_Rights_Based_Approach_to_Development_Cooperation_Towards_a_Common_Understanding_Among_UN.pdf http://www.undg.org/archive_docs/6959-The_Human_Rights_Based_Approach_to_Development_Cooperation_Towards_a_Common_Understanding_Among_UN.pdf http://www.fao.org/righttofood/kc/downloads/vl/docs/212951.pdf http://www.un.org/largerfreedom/ http://www.undp.org/governance/docs/HRPN_English.pdf The World Bank Legal Review136 Mainstreaming mechanism, supported by a multidonor trust fund, to coor- dinate UN systemwide work on human rights in development cooperation. Human Rights Obligations as a Policy Frame Some policies integrate human rights explicitly in terms of international law obligations. In these policies, human rights have potentially far-reaching impli- cations because the policies rely on the legally binding quality of human rights to ground their approach, even if the references are more general and operate as an overall frame. For example, a tenet of the Austrian Development Coop- eration (ADC) Human Rights Policy Document (2006) establishes “[h]uman rights as a normative principle, as a programming principle, and as an in- strument for evaluating interventions.” The ADC policy states: “A stronger link between these two areas offers a legally based framework and a planning instrument for policies and programs. It steers the focus in poverty reduction away from the needs of the poor towards the obligations of the state and the capabilities/potential of citizens to demand their rights.” Like a number of other bilateral aid agencies, the Swedish International Development Coopera- tion Agency (SIDA) has a well-established practice of mainstreaming human rights.83 In keeping with this practice, Sweden’s policy for democratic devel- opment and human rights in Swedish development cooperation84 highlights the human rights perspective,85 which it defines based on the UN Universal Declaration of Human Rights and international and regional human rights conventions, and further confirms that “[a]lthough contradictions or tension may exist between different rights, states cannot choose to disregard certain of their obligations under international law.”86 New Zealand’s International Aid and Development Agency document Human Rights Policy Statement (2002) and its Human Rights Implementa- tion Plan of Action 2004–09 similarly confirm the role of donor and partner human rights treaty obligations in linking human rights and development. Likewise, the policy of German development cooperation rests on common human rights law obligations. Germany’s Development Policy Action Plan www.undp.org/governance/docs/HRPN_English.pdf. The UNDP Strategic Plan, 2008–11 makes numerous references to human rights and clarifies the role of the program: “16. Un- derscores that while UNDP should uphold universal United Nations norms and standards, including those related to human rights, UNDP does not have any normative or monitor- ing role with regard to human rights.” UNDP Strategic Plan, 2008–2011: Accelerating Global Progress on Human Development, DP/2007/43/Rev.1, 4 (May 22, 2008). More generally, see E. Mandeville, United Nations Development Programme, in Encyclopedia of Human Rights 150 –57 (D. Forsythe ed., Oxford U. Press 2009). 83 See, for example, Uggla, supra note 73. 84 Memorandum Appendix to Government Decision 2010-01-2 (UF2009/33076/UP). “With this policy, the Government is raising its level of ambition and clarifying its aims concerning Swedish development cooperation in working towards the goal of democratic development and greater respect for human rights in developing countries.” 85 See Munro, supra note 74. 86 SIDA, Memorandum Appendix to Government Decision 2010-01-2, 6. http://www.undp.org/governance/docs/HRPN_English.pdf Human Rights and Development 137 on Human Rights 2008–2010 highlights the shared obligations of donors and partners under human rights treaties: Human rights provide us with legally binding standards to which we, in common with our partner countries, have committed our- selves inside and outside our borders. We have jointly ratified inter- national human rights treaties and so it is our joint responsibility to work for the respect, protection and fulfillment of human rights. By meeting our obligations, we want to help our partners specifically and effectively to meet theirs.87 The 2011 BMZ strategy paper Human Rights in German Development Policy supports this view, affirming that human rights form the overarching framework for development policy. It states that the implementation of hu- man rights conventions is a legally binding obligation and that this “provides the binding frame of reference for Germany’s development cooperation with partner countries.”88 Among multilaterals, the UN system’s human rights approach89 and UN guidance in development activities are broadly based on human rights treaty obligations,90 even if the broader question of the UN’s own human rights ob- ligations remains contested.91 A sophisticated example is UNICEF’s human rights–based programming approach, which treats the Convention on the Rights of the Child (CRC) as a central programming document, relying on it di- rectly and explicitly. In addition, although the Committee on the Rights of the Child is the monitoring body established by the CRC, and although UNICEF does not have a formal role in monitoring CRC compliance, UNICEF has, over time, become active in all stages of the reporting process. In this respect, the UNICEF example illustrates the possibility of institutional coordination be- tween development programming and treaty monitoring activities. The position of other international organizations has similarly signaled broader recognition of the role of human rights in development. The OECD Development Assistance Committee’s (2007) Action-Oriented Policy Paper on Human Rights and Development (AOPP) is predicated on a vision of human rights as integral to development and of human rights and equitable, sus- tainable development being mutually reinforcing. This approach is squarely 87 BMZ, Development Policy Action Plan on Human Rights 2008–2010, 4. The policy also includes a comprehensive list of human rights treaty resources (18–19). 88 BMZ Human Rights in German Development Policy, BMZ Strategy Paper 4, introductory summary, paragraph 2 (2009). 89 See supra note 77. 90 See, for example, UNDAF guidelines available at www.undg.org. Within the UNDG, imple- menting a human rights–based approach to development programming is the focus of the Human Rights Mainstreaming Mechanism (HRM); see also the UN Common Learning Pack- age on Human Rights–Based Approach. 91 For a thorough and thoughtful analysis of this question in the context of the UN’s develop- ment operations, see M. Darrow & L. Arbour, The Pillar of Glass: Human Rights in the Develop- ment Operations of the United Nations, 103 Am. J. Intl. L. 446 (2009). www.undg.org The World Bank Legal Review138 based on the international human rights law framework: “Human rights con- stitute a unique, internationally shared and accepted normative framework, reflecting global moral and political values. International human rights law has evolved to protect and safeguard the integrity and dignity of the person, by establishing legal obligations on states.” The first of 10 principles, intended to serve as a basic orientation on human rights in key development areas and activities where donor harmonization is of particular relevance, states: “Build a shared understanding of the links between human rights obligations and development priorities through dialogue.” Another acknowledgment of the place of human rights obligations in de- velopment policy, albeit indirectly and from a private sector perspective, is the International Finance Corporation (IFC) Policy on Enviromental and Social Sustainability, which is part of the IFC Sustainability Framework.92 The 2012 policy recognizes the responsibility of business to respect human rights inde- pendently of state duties to respect, protect, and fulfill human rights.93 In a footnote to the term “human rights,” the policy states that “for the purposes of this Policy, IFC shall be guided by the International Bill of Rights and the eight core conventions of the International Labour Organization.”94 Human Rights as Operational Norms in Development Policy Frameworks Despite the broad support for human rights adduced in the policies reviewed above, not all such provisions translate into a reliance on human rights in a direct operational sense. Indeed, not all agencies with human rights–related policies accept that they are under a legal obligation to promote and respect human rights, and intrinsic arguments for including human rights in develop- ment cooperation are not always limited to legal ones.95 Subtle differences in terminology are also discernible in some policies’ treatment of human rights in terms of responsibilities rather than in more definite legal terms such as obligations with specific policy consequences resulting from their invocation. The policies of a number of agencies and institutions are distinguished by the strength of the legal and policy provisions integrating human rights, with the potential for significant operational implications. At their strongest, such policies emphasize human rights as a shared legal framework, highlight- ing both partner and donor obligations under international human rights law and offering concrete operational entry points for their application in devel- opment activities. 92 http://www1.ifc.org/wps/wcm/connect/Topics_Ext_Content/IFC_External_Corporate _site/IFC+Sustainability/Sustainability+Framework. 93 IFC Policy on Environmental and Social Sustainability ( Jan. 1, 2012), paragraph 12, avail- able at http://www1.ifc.org/wps/wcm/connect/7540778049a792dcb87efaa8c6a8312a/SP _English_2012.pdf?MOD=AJPERES. 94 Id. 95 OECD DAC, Integrating Human Rights into Development: Donor Approaches, Challenges and Ex- periences 29 (OEDC 2006), study by L.-H. Piron & T. O’Neil. http://www1.ifc.org/wps/wcm/connect/Topics_Ext_Content/IFC_External_Corporate_site/IFC+Sustainability/Sustainability+Framework http://www1.ifc.org/wps/wcm/connect/7540778049a792dcb87efaa8c6a8312a/SP_English_2012.pdf?MOD=AJPERES http://www1.ifc.org/wps/wcm/connect/Topics_Ext_Content/IFC_External_Corporate_site/IFC+Sustainability/Sustainability+Framework http://www1.ifc.org/wps/wcm/connect/7540778049a792dcb87efaa8c6a8312a/SP_English_2012.pdf?MOD=AJPERES Human Rights and Development 139 The European Union provides an example of a policy approach connect- ing the dictates of the international human rights law frameworks and the pol- icy requirements applicable in development cooperation. Although its trade and external policies have been critiqued for internal incoherencies,96 for their potential negative impacts on human rights in developing countries,97 and for failing to fully integrate human rights, the EU has, since 1995, adopted “a distinct policy” on human rights in its external relations. As a result a human rights clause98 is introduced into all trade and development agreements with third countries or nonmembers,99 making the protection of human rights an es- sential element of any trade and development agreement.100 As with a number of the bilateral examples discussed above, the centrality of human rights to EU development cooperation draws explicitly on legal commitments that are both internal and external to the EU itself,101 anchoring human rights opera- tionally in development through the treaty obligations of member states.102 Thus, Article 9 of the Cotonou Agreement makes the respect of human rights an essential element of the agreement, basing that clause explicitly on interna- tional obligations and commitments concerning respect for human rights.103 96 B. Mahnkopf, EU Multilateral Trade Policy: Neither Coherent nor Development Friendly, Global Labour University Working Paper No. 2 (Feb. 2008). 97 J. Nwobike, The Application of Human Rights in African Caribbean and Pacific–European Union Development and Trade Partnership, 6(10) German L.J. 1381 (2005). Examples include the fu- ture potential human rights impact (ex ante study) of EU economic partnership agreements on dairy and honey farmers in Zambia and the right to food of milk and maize farmers in Uganda (2009). 98 “The essential element” of an agreement, or the “human rights essential element clause.” See EU Council Decision 7255/95. Human Rights Clauses in Community Agreements with Non- member Countries (May 24, 1995). See also Commission Communication on the Inclusion of Respect for Democratic Principles and Human Rights in Agreements between the Commu- nity and Third Countries COM (95) 216 (May 23, 1995). 99 M. Cremona, Human Rights and Democracy Clauses in the EC’s Trade Agreements, in The Euro- pean Union and World Trade Law after the GATT Uruguay Round (N. Emiliou & D. O’Keefe ed., Wiley 1996); E. Reidel & M. Will, Human Rights Clauses in External Agreements of the EC, in The EU and Human Rights (P. Alston ed., Oxford U. Press 1999). 100 See also Cotonou Agreement—partnership agreement between the EC and ACP countries, concluded in 2000, a revised version of which entered into force on July 1, 2008. Negotiations for a second round of revisions were concluded on March 19, 2010. 101 http://www.ihrnetwork.org/eu-development-policies_215.htm. Internal commitments are based on the Treaty on European Union and were confirmed in the Treaty of Amsterdam and the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights and the European Instrument for Democratization and Human Rights (2006). 102 According to the International Human Rights Network, “Human rights are central to EU Development Cooperation matching similar commitments to its humanitarian aid and Common Foreign and Security Policy. The policies flow from the legal obligations of its Member States, as well as from EU treaty provisions which recognize human rights as com- mon values underpinning EU partnership and dialogue with third countries.” See http:// www.ihrnetwork.org/eu-development-policies_215.htm. 103 Article 9 of the Cotonou Agreement provides: Essential Elements and Fundamental Element 1. Cooperation shall be directed towards sustainable development centered on the hu- man person, who is the main protagonist and beneficiary of development; this entails http://www.ihrnetwork.org/eu-development-policies_215.htm http://www.ihrnetwork.org/eu-development-policies_215.htm http://www.ihrnetwork.org/eu-development-policies_215.htm The World Bank Legal Review140 The centrality of human rights treaties is similarly reflected in the 2007 EU European Instrument for Democracy and Human Rights. This instrument establishes a mechanism under which the community provides assistance within the framework of the community’s policy on development coopera- tion and economic, financial, and technical cooperation with third countries, consistent with EU foreign policy as a whole, contributing to the develop- ment and consolidation of democracy and the rule of law and of respect for all human rights and fundamental freedoms.104 The instrument draws directly from international and regional human rights legal frameworks,105 and its aims are squarely based on human rights106 and the international and regional legal frameworks that enforce them.107 Other developments in the EU con- text reveal the increasing relevance of international human rights standards respect for and promotion of all human rights. Respect for all human rights and fun- damental freedoms, including respect for fundamental social rights, democracy based on the rule of law and transparent and accountable governance are an integral part of sustainable development. 2. The Parties refer to their international obligations and commitments concerning re- spect for human rights. They reiterate their deep attachment to human dignity and human rights, which are legitimate aspirations of individuals and peoples. Human rights are universal, indivisible and inter-related. The Parties undertake to promote and protect all fundamental freedoms and human rights, be they civil and political, or economic, social and cultural. In this context, the Parties reaffirm the equality of men and women. . . . Respect for human rights, democratic principles and the rule of law, which underpin the ACP-EU Partnership, shall underpin the domestic and interna- tional policies of the Parties and constitute the essential elements of this Agreement. . . . These areas will also be a focus of support for development strategies. The Community shall provide support for political, institutional and legal reforms and for building the capacity of public and private actors and civil society in the framework of strategies agreed jointly between the State concerned and the Community. 104 Regulation (EC) No. 1889/2006 of the European Parliament and of the Council of December 20, 2006, on establishing a financing instrument for the promotion of democracy and human rights worldwide, 29.12.2006 EN Official J. of the European Union L. 386/1. 105 Paragraph 7 provides: “The Community’s contribution to the development and consolida- tion of democracy and the rule of law, and of respect for human rights and fundamental freedoms is rooted in the general principles established by the International Bill of Human Rights, and any other human rights instrument adopted within the framework of the United Nations, as well as relevant regional human rights Instruments.” 106 Paragraph 2(a) provides: “Such assistance shall aim in particular at (a) enhancing the re- spect for and observance of human rights and fundamental freedoms, as proclaimed in the Universal Declaration of Human Rights and other international and regional human rights instruments.” 107 Paragraph 2(b) provides: “Such assistance shall aim in particular at (a) enhancing the re- spect for and observance of human rights and fundamental freedoms, as proclaimed in the Universal Declaration of Human Rights and other international and regional human rights instruments.” However, it is worth noting that the recent EU Communication on the MDGs does not highlight the role of human rights frameworks in any significant way, other than to mention that “[MDGs] emphasize the importance of a Human Rights based approach to development.” European Commisssion, A Twelve-Point EU Action Plan in Support of the Mil- lennium Development Goals, Communication from the Commission to the European Parliament, the Council, the European Economic and Social Committee and the Regions, 6 (2010). See also Annual Action Programme 2011 for the European Instrument for the Promotion of Democracy and Human Rights Worldwide (EU Commission Mar. 29, 2011). Human Rights and Development 141 in fostering sustainable development in EU trade policy. Examples include the European Parliament resolution that encourages greater cooperation at the multinational level between the World Trade Organization (WTO) and the main UN institutions in the human rights field. This resolution states that the Parliament considers that closer links with the Office of the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights via special procedures would be par- ticularly useful to provide a multilateral trade framework that would enhance respect for human rights and considers, similarly, that the high commission’s expertise could be taken into account by WTO panels and the appeals body when cases of serious breaches of human rights are observed. In addition, the Parliament’s resolution considers that the Human Rights Council’s universal periodic review should be a useful tool to monitor compliance with human rights provisions in international trade agreements and supports the practice of including legally binding human rights clauses in the EU’s international agreements.108 The EU development policy landscape was further defined by new poli- cies on the future of development policy and the instrument of budget support in October 2011. Increasing the Impact of EU Development Policy: An Agenda for Change seeks to focus aid on fewer countries and fewer sectors while prioritiz- ing human rights, democracy, and other key elements of good governance.109 The EU Commission’s 2011 position on budget support to third countries110 reiterates the linkage between human rights and development, indicating that its proposed approach “would lead to enhanced importance of human rights, democracy and good governance trends in determining the mix of instru- ments and aid modalities at country level.”111 The European Investment Bank (EIB) provides another example of broad legal and policy commitment to human rights. As an EU institution, EIB is bound by the EU Charter of Fundamental Rights and takes the charter as a point of departure.112 EIB policy integrates an approach to human rights focused on respect for environmental, social, and economic rights and takes 108 European Parliament resolution of November 25, 2010, on human rights and social and en- vironmental standards in international trade agreements (2009/2219 [INI]). For a critical view of the traditional models on the value added of human rights in trade, see A. Lang, The Role of the Human Rights Movement in Trade Policy-Making: Human Rights as a Trigger for Policy Learning, 5 New Zealand J. Pub. Intl. Law. 77–102 (2007). 109 European Commission, Increasing the Impact of EU Development Policy: An Agenda for Change (EU Commission Oct. 13, 2011), available at http://ec.europa.eu/europeaid/what/devel opment-policies/documents/agenda_for_change_en.pdf. 110 European Commission, The Future Approach to EU Budget Support to Third Countries (EU Commission Oct. 13, 2011). 111 The policy provides that “the EU should assess whether pre-conditions exist to entrust Good Governance and Development Contracts to a partner country, i.e.; whether fundamental values of human rights, democracy and rule of law or a clear path towards international standards exist and whether such a Contract could clearly act as a driver to accelerate this movement.” 112 http://www.eib.org/about/news/business-and-human-rights.htm. http://ec.europa.eu/europeaid/what/development-policies/documents/agenda_for_change_en.pdf http://www.eib.org/about/news/business-and-human-rights.htm http://ec.europa.eu/europeaid/what/development-policies/documents/agenda_for_change_en.pdf The World Bank Legal Review142 human rights considerations into account in its project evaluations. The EIB is reviewing its existing project social performance standards in light of the prin- ciples of the UN Respect, Protect, and Remedy framework113 and will update existing project guidelines and operational practices based on the outcome of that review. The direct links between human rights and development frameworks are evident in the 2005 framework document of the New Economic Partnership for Africa’s Development (NEPAD),114 which contains several references to hu- man rights as a foundation,115 objective, and responsibility of the mechanism. It recognizes that “development is impossible in the absence of true demo- cracy, respect for human rights, peace, and good governance.”116 The African Peer Review Mechanism (APRM),117 which operates as part of the NEPAD, links the final stage of its review to existing human rights mechanisms such as the African Commission on Human Rights.118 In this, the African-led policy is an example of a framework that explicitly links development with human rights and human rights obligations as well as the regional institutional mech- anism that monitors them.119 Some donors specify that human rights obligations operate as minimum legal standards against which their development activities are judged for con- sistency. In these instances, human rights treaty obligations are operationally connected with the core of development cooperation policies and activities. An example of this is Canada’s 2008 Official Development Assistance Account- ability Act, which contains a human rights clause requiring development op- erations financed by Canada to be consistent with international human rights standards.120 113 See infra note 164. 114 http://www.nepad.org/home/lang/en. 115 Id., paragraph 180. The NEPAD has, as one of its foundations, the expansion of democratic frontiers and the deepening of the culture of human rights. A democratic Africa will become a pillar of world democracy, human rights, and tolerance. The resources of the world cur- rently dedicated to resolving civil and interstate conflict could therefore be freed for more rewarding endeavors. 116 Id., paragraph 79. 117 An important accountability-related mechanism to the NEPAD, the APRM is an instru- ment voluntarily acceded to by member states of the African Union (AU) as an African self- monitoring mechanism. The APRM is central to the NEPAD process for the socioeconomic development of Africa. 118 The APRM base document, available at http://www.chr.up.ac.za/hr_docs/aprm/docs /book3.pdf, Article 25, states: “Six months after the report has been considered by the Heads of State and Government of the participating member countries, it should be formally and publicly tabled in key regional and sub-regional structures such as the Pan-African Parliament, the African Commission on Human and Peoples’ Rights, the envisaged Peace and Security Council and the Economic, Social and Cultural Council (ECOSOCC) of the African Union.” 119 See analogies with the IDB policy linkages to the Inter-American Court of Human Rights discussed in the subsection References to Human Rights. 120 Canada, 2008 Official Development Assistance Accountability Act, which came into force on June 28, 2008, states in Section 4(1): “Official development assistance may be provided only if http://www.chr.up.ac.za/hr_docs/aprm/docs/book3.pdf http://www.nepad.org/home/lang/en http://www.chr.up.ac.za/hr_docs/aprm/docs/book3.pdf Human Rights and Development 143 The European Bank for Reconstruction and Development (EBRD) adopts a similar approach, establishing direct operational implications for human rights obligations in development activities. Unlike other multilateral devel- opment banks (MDBs), the Agreement Establishing the EBRD sets forth a po- litical mandate for the EBRD to further the transition to multiparty democracy and to encourage a respect for human rights, making an explicit provision for human rights in its preamble.121 Thus, “the preamble and the phrasing of Ar- ticle 1 seem to imply that the founding members expected that the EBRD in its operations would be sensitive to the human rights of residents in the countries of its operation.”122 Building on its foundational agreement, the EBRD’s 2008 Environmental and Social Policy incorporates human rights as a minimum standard defined in accordance with human rights instruments. “The EBRD will not knowingly finance projects that would contravene obligations under international treaties and agreements related to environmental protection, human rights and sustainable development as identified through project appraisal.”123 The fact that the baseline underpinning this policy is rooted in human rights treaties has not insulated the EBRD from NGO criticism that the Bank’s commitment to human rights is weak in practice.124 A similar example is found in the Council of Europe Development Bank (CEB), administered under the authority of the Council of Europe, which has the protection and promotion of human rights as one of its principal aims. the competent minister is of the opinion that it (a) contributes to poverty reduction; (b) takes into account the perspectives of the poor; and (c) is consistent with international human rights standards.” 121 The preamble of the agreement establishing the EBRD provides that contracting parties are: [c]ommitted to the fundamental principles of multiparty democracy, the rule of law, re- spect for human rights and market economics; . . . Welcoming the intent of Central and Eastern European countries to further the practical implementation of multiparty de- mocracy, strengthening democratic institutions, the rule of law and respect for human rights and their willingness to implement reforms in order to evolve towards market- oriented economies. Article 1 provides: Purpose In contributing to economic progress and reconstruction, the purpose of the Bank shall be to foster the transition towards open market-oriented economies and to promote private and entrepreneurial initiative in the Central and Eastern European countries committed to and applying the principles of multiparty democracy, pluralism and mar- ket economics. 122 A. McAuley, European Bank for Reconstruction and Development, in Oxford Encyclopedia of Human Rights vol. 2, 169, 171 (D. Forsythe ed., Oxford U. Press 2009). 123 EBRD, Environmental and Social Policy, paragraph 9. Paragraph 37 specifies that EBRD’s country and sector strategies should summarize the principal environmental, human rights, gender equality, and other social issues in the relevant country or sector and sets out the EBRD’s proposals for taking these issues into account in its operations, where appropriate. See http://www.ebrd.org/pages/about/principles/sustainability/policy.shtml. 124 For a brief discussion of such critiques, see A. McAuley, The European Bank for Reconstruction and Development, in Oxford Encyclopedia of Human Rights 172 (D. Forsythe ed., Oxford U. Press 2009). http://www.ebrd.org/pages/about/principles/sustainability/policy.shtml The World Bank Legal Review144 The CEB is institutionally grounded in human rights, and the secretary gen- eral of the Council of Europe is required to review all project applications to assess whether they conform to the political and social aims of the Council of Europe. Thus, the CEB’s human rights framework includes loan regula- tions that require projects to conform to provisions of the Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms and the European Social Charter. 125 In addition, the CEB Environmental Policy, which describes the environmental and social principles that guide its project-related opera- tions, connects socially and environmentally sustainable development to hu- man rights and mandates that “the CEB will not knowingly finance projects which are identified as undermining human rights.”126 In a similar vein, albeit domestically rather than externally focused, the Council of Europe Parliamen- tary Assembly adopted a resolution inviting its 47 member states to be guided by OHCHR’s 2006 Principles and Guidelines on a Human Rights Approach to Poverty Reduction in their policymaking and budget decisions.127 Human Rights and Development: Initial Observations on Regime Interaction As the foregoing review illustrates, the interaction of human rights and de- velopment regimes is significant and increasing but widely divergent. It is difficult, however, to discern an automatic consequence from the mere men- tion of human rights (or even human rights obligations) in a development pol- icy framework. Even the adoption of a human rights policy or human rights mainstreaming approach does not necessarily have immediate or concrete op- erational consequences. Not every such policy or provision requires particular forms of assessments or analyses, nor will each generate specific guidelines or parameters in financing decisions or dialogues. The review reveals the limited engagement of most development policy frameworks with human rights as binding legal obligations. In many instances, human rights are referred to in general or preambular terms; in others, they receive mention as principles or cross-cutting themes—none of which has a clear legally binding underpinning. Moreover, more explicit and elaborate ar- ticulations of the links between human rights and development, such as in 125 CEB, Policy for Loan and Project Financing, adopted June 2006 under Administrative Council Resolution 1495, Council of Europe, Paris, available at http://www.coebank.org /Upload/legal/en/ppfp_english.pdf. These CEB contractual covenants are a unique fea- ture: CEB can suspend, cancel, and/or demand early reimbursement of a loan if a project’s implementation leads to a human rights violation. (See, for example, Article 3.3(g)(iii) of the CEB loan regulations.) 126 CEB, Environmental Policy, available at http://www.coebank.org/Upload/infocentre /brochure/en/environmental_policy.pdf#search=%22environmental%22. 127 Council of Europe Parliamentary Report and Draft Resolution, Doc. 12555, Combating Pov- erty (Mar. 28, 2012), paragraph 7, provides: “The Assembly strongly supports the Principles and Guidelines for a Human Rights Approach to Poverty Reduction Strategies proposed by the Office of the United Nations High Commissioner for Human Rights (UNHCHR) and invites member states to take due account of the Guidelines in their public policymaking and relevant budgetary decisions.” http://www.coebank.org/Upload/legal/en/ppfp_english.pdf http://www.coebank.org/Upload/infocentre/brochure/en/environmental_policy.pdf#search=%22environmental%22 http://www.coebank.org/Upload/legal/en/ppfp_english.pdf http://www.coebank.org/Upload/infocentre/brochure/en/environmental_policy.pdf#search=%22environmental%22 Human Rights and Development 145 the declaration of the right to development and the various resolutions built upon it, are not legally binding. Most of the policy examples that integrate hu- man rights obligations do so in ways confined to particular policies, themes, or groups, or in a manner so general that their specific impacts are hard to identify. The operational impacts of human rights legal obligations are only beginning to be explored in policies like those of the European Union or Can- ada, where human rights obligations are operative in a direct legal and policy sense and they trigger some immediate consequence or action. In addition, although the trend in both political statements and develop- ment policies appears to be greater integration of human rights in develop- ment policy and a gradual recognition of the potential relevance of human rights obligations in development contexts, the majority of development pol- icy frameworks evidence the separability of human rights and development and the fragmentation of international law. Human Rights, Development, and the Fragmentation of International Law Fragmentation of International Law: Causes and Consequences Why are there such significant divergences and disconnects between human rights and development? Why do these disconnects persist when the same countries are parties to the human rights treaties and members of develop- ment agencies and banks?128 The reasons are similar to those underpinning the fragmentation of law in general. Some practitioners opine that not only has there never been a single global legislature or appellate court to mold a unified body of law, but there has never been a uniform will for such a sys- tem. Instead, states have implicitly or explicitly conceived of particular issues and problems and responded by agreeing to new laws and supporting inter- national organizations.129 Some observers go further and argue that the “un- wieldy and intransigent nature of regimes is often intentional and may reflect a wish by powerful states to protect their dominance.”130 Other reasons for fragmentation and impediments to coherent regime interaction include lack of coordination at the domestic level, states adopting inconsistent national po- sitions across different international fora, and a lack of transparency within particular regimes.131 128 On the diversity of policy formulations that emanate from international organizations, see Alston, supra note 17, at 95–106, who argues that diversity can be explained by “a desire to maintain as much policy flexibility as possible. This helps to accommodate a broad array of approaches on the part of different governments, gives the organization itself considerable leeway to define or redefine its priorities, and makes it easier to move away from failed poli- cies towards new ones” (97). 129 M. Young, Introduction, in Young, supra note 1, at 2. 130 Id., at 10. 131 Young, supra note 1, at 95. The World Bank Legal Review146 The specific reasons for the divergences between human rights and de- velopment regimes are thus complex and multifaceted, varying across institu- tions and over time.132 They are often connected with historically entrenched understandings of institutional roles and mandates133 and linked to the pre- dominance of different disciplines, evidence bases, premises, and values within those different regimes.134 “Functional differentiation leads to path de- pendency, higher transaction costs, ‘tunnel vision’ and even solipsistic and imperial tendencies within regimes.”135 The separateness may be rooted in legal factors, such as the emergence of the relevant frameworks at different times; the fact that laws (treaties) are implemented by different institutions with different powers of enforcement and relative strengths; the absence of a uniform ratification of the laws (treaties) by all member states;136 and the fact that the laws aim to fulfill particular sets of preferences within the interna- tional legal system that may not be in harmony.137 In the case of development agencies, these factors are underscored by es- tablished legal interpretations of constitutive instruments, which in some cases include strong political prohibitions that have special relevance for human rights.138 Governments take very different positions on human rights, even more so when human rights are connected with development interventions or aid resource allocations. Indeed, the reluctance to connect development co- operation policies and activities with human rights legal obligations may be attributable to the clarity, enforceability, and lack of flexibility such obligations impose. They may also be reinforced by perceptions of human rights obliga- tions as less amenable to measurement or less empirically based. What are the consequences of such fragmentation? What practical prob- lems or risks does it generate, and how do these translate for human rights in the context of development? 132 S. McInerney-Lankford, Human Rights and Development: Some Institutional Perspectives, 25(3) Netherlands Q. Hum. Rights 459 (2007). 133 Y. Yokata, Non-political Character of the World Bank, 20 Japanese Ann. Intl. L. 39 (1976). 134 See D. Seymour & J. Pincus, Human Rights and Economics: The Conceptual Basis for Their Com- plementarity, 4 Dev. Pol. Rev. 387–405 (2008). 135 Young, Introduction, in Young, supra note 1, at 11. 136 See discussion of parallel membership below. 137 Young, supra note 1, at 88–89. 138 See, for example, in relation to the IBRD, I. Shihata, Political Activity Prohibited, in World Bank Legal Papers 219–44 (Martinus Nijhoff 2000); I. Shihata, The Exclusion of Political Consideration in the Bank’s Articles—Its Meaning and Scope in the Context of the Institutional Evolution, in The World Bank in a Changing World: Selected Essays 62–78 (Martinus Nijhoff 1995). Also relevant in this context is I. Shihata, Human Rights, Development and International Financial Institutions, in The World Bank in a Changing World: Selected Essays and Lectures Volume II 553–78 (Martinus Nijhoff 1995), to be contrasted with EBRD, Political Aspects of the Mandate of the European Bank for Reconstruction and Development (1991), available at http://www.ebrd.org/pages /research/publications/institutional/procedures.shtml, and Political Aspects of the Mandate of the European Bank for Reconstruction and Development in Relation to Ethnic Minorities (1991), available at http://www.ebrd.org/pages/research/publications/institutional/ethnic.shtml. http://www.ebrd.org/pages/research/publications/institutional/procedures.shtml http://www.ebrd.org/pages/research/publications/institutional/ethnic.shtml http://www.ebrd.org/pages/research/publications/institutional/procedures.shtml Human Rights and Development 147 Although some commentators have argued that fragmentation is inevi- table139 and endemic to international law,140 and others note the ways in which it may benefit specialized regimes,141 many point to the risks of systemic ambi- guity and incoherence. The first and most obvious consequence of fragmenta- tion is the undermining of coherence in international law in general and in- ternational policy coherence in particular.142 Policy coherence aims to prevent duplication and avoid contradiction in government policy actions by promot- ing consistency across related subject matters and assessing the impacts of di- verse areas of international policy on one another.143 It operates both vertically —ensuring that states implement treaty obligations through laws, policies, and processes—and horizontally—ensuring that state policies across sectors, departments, or ministries are consistent or compatible with one another. Promoting international policy coherence is an objective of growing im- portance for international development agencies and organizations. In the context of development, this objective aims to “ensure that government poli- cies are mutually supportive of the countries’ development goals.”144 It implies “strengthening synergies and weeding out inconsistencies between non-aid policies and development objectives.”145 The EU has made policy coherence a point of emphasis in development, particularly since the Lisbon Treaty;146 in 139 A growing body of literature is emerging on global administrative law that addresses, among other themes, the constraints and enduring reasons for “nonconvergence” and assesses the normative case for and against the promotion of a unified field of global administrative law; see, for example, B. Kingsbury, N. Krisch, & R. Stewart, The Emergence of Global Administrative Law, 68 L. & Contem. Probs. 15 (2005); and B. Kingsbury, Introduction: Global Administrative Law in the Institutional Practice of Global Regulatory Governance, in World Bank Legal Review International Financial Institutions and Global Legal Governance 3 –33 (World Bank 2011). 140 S. Humphreys, Technology Transfer in Three Regimes, in Young, supra note 1, at 195, citing the ILC Study Group, supra note 42. 141 B. Simma, Fragmentation in a Positive Light, 25 Mich. J. Intl. L. 845 (2004). 142 See, for example, M. Salomon, Global Responsibility for Human Rights 106 (Oxford U. Press 2007). 143 http://www.oecd.org/document/54/0,2340,en_2649_33721_35320054_1_1_1_1,00.html. This idea has relevance to efforts in the UN human rights mechanisms to enhance coherence and harmonization among treaty bodies; see UN Report of the Working Group on Harmonisa- tion of Working Methods of Treaty Bodies ( Jan. 9, 2007); Report on Working Methods of the Hu- man Rights Treaty Bodies Relating to State Party Reporting Processes: Note by the Secretariat, HRI /MC/2007/4 ( Jun. 1, 2007); and Report on the Implementation of Recommendations of the 5th Intercommittee Meeting and the 18th Meeting of Chair Persons, Note by the Secretariat, HRI /MC/2007/6 (May 29, 2007). 144 OECD, Declaration on Policy Coherence for Development, C/MIN(2008)2/FINAL ( Jun. 4, 2008). 145 European Commission, EU 2011 Report on Policy Coherence for Development, Commission Staff Working Paper (Dec. 15, 2011). 146 Article 208 of the Lisbon Treaty requires that “[t]he Union shall take account of the objec- tives of development cooperation in the policies that it implements which are likely to affect developing countries.” Some observers have voiced criticism of the implementation of this objective, including in relation to human rights. See http://coherence.concordeurope.org /pdf/Concord_Report_15_AW_LORES.pdf. See also EU Report on Policy Coherence for Devel- opment (2007), available at http://ec.europa.eu/development/icenter/repository/Publica tion_Coherence_DEF_en.pdf. http://www.oecd.org/document/54/0,2340,en_2649_33721_35320054_1_1_1_1,00.html http://coherence.concordeurope.org/pdf/Concord_Report_15_AW_LORES.pdf http://ec.europa.eu/development/icenter/repository/Publication_Coherence_DEF_en.pdf http://coherence.concordeurope.org/pdf/Concord_Report_15_AW_LORES.pdf http://ec.europa.eu/development/icenter/repository/Publication_Coherence_DEF_en.pdf The World Bank Legal Review148 May 2010, the European Parliament created the Standing Rapporteur on Policy Coherence for Development, responsible for facilitating interaction between the parliamentary committee on development and other committees. Policy coherence for development focal points have also been appointed within the European Commission Directorates-General and the External Action Service. In 2008, the ministers of Organization for Economic Cooperation and Development (OECD) countries issued a Declaration on Policy Coherence for Development, which acknowledges the increased economic interdepen- dence among countries, as well as between development policies and oth- er areas of public policy.147 Although it does not mention human rights, the declaration stresses the importance of policy coherence in achieving interna- tionally agreed-upon development goals, including those contained in the Millennium Declaration,148 which includes commitments related to human rights. The OECD launched an international platform for policy coherence in development:149 “OECD countries recognize the need for greater coherence in policies across sectors that affect developing countries. Aid alone cannot address the needs of the developing world. Policies in areas like agriculture, trade, investment, migration and others have a profound impact on develop- ing countries, yet they often work at cross-purposes.” Fragmentation and policy incoherence are apposite in the context of hu- man rights, including threats to “the quality and coherence of international law as a whole and resulting in serious conflicts and tensions between pro- grammes and principles.”150 Such fragmentation has potential impacts on the levels of protection afforded by international human rights law through the emergence of “special normative regimes in various areas of technical cooper- ation described as ‘self contained’ in order to highlight their operation outside the general international law.”151 This in turn potentially leads to “the erosion of international law, conflicting jurisprudence, forum shopping and the loss of legal security”;152 some argue that it undermines the international rule of law.153 It is not inconceivable that development and human rights regimes yield different interpretations of the same rule of international law, which risks gen- 147 OECD, Policy Coherence for Development. 148 For example, paragraph 4. Paragraph 9 contains states’ pledge to “ensure the implementa- tion, by States Parties, of treaties in areas such as arms control and disarmament and of international humanitarian law and human rights law.” See also paragraphs 24–26 and 30. 149 http://www.oecd.org/department/0,3355,en_2649_18532957_1_1_1_1_1,00.html. 150 I. Brownlie, The Rights of Peoples in Modern International Law, in The Rights of Peoples 1, 15 ( J. Crawford ed., Clarendon Press 1988). 151 B. Simma, Self Contained Regimes, 15 Netherlands Yearbook Intl. L. 111, 136 (1985); Kosken- niemi & Leino, infra note 154, at 560. 152 ILC Study Group, supra note 42, paragraph 9. 153 M. Scheinin, Human Rights Treaties and the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties—Conflicts or Harmony, in The Status of International Treaties on Human Rights 43 –45 (Venice Commission ed., Council of European Publishing 2006). http://www.oecd.org/department/0,3355,en_2649_18532957_1_1_1_1_1,00.html Human Rights and Development 149 erating confusion and even injustice.154 This has led some observers to point to the risk of a lower standard of protection due to a special regime not tak- ing into account more detailed guidance or robust protection provided for in general law or by other organizations.155 Others point to the failure to assess human rights impacts of policy measures, noting the potentially detrimental consequences for human rights in developing countries.156 The growth of development law or policy-making processes alongside the proliferation of human rights law and standards exemplifies the phenomenon of the fragmentation of international law. The growing reach of development policy and transgovernmental regulation157 into areas governed by human rights treaties increases the likelihood of regime interaction between human rights and development, as evidenced in the substantive and policy overlaps described above. The potential for norm conflict is a growing problem inher- ent in the fragmentation of international law due to the partial and poorly un- derstood points of convergence between human rights and development re- gimes and the lack of clarity around operational implications of human rights provisions in development frameworks. This situation is heightened by the neglect of human rights obligations and the absence of a clear, governing legal baseline where regimes do interact and their norms conflict. The fragmentation in general and these specific consequences in particu- lar generate a risk of accountability gaps158 for human rights in development processes and outcomes.159 Although rights and accountability interact in complex ways in any setting, and although they play an especially complex and dynamic role in development,160 the point here is that neglecting rights 154 M. Koskenniemi & P. Leino, Fragmentation of International Law? Postmodern Anxieties, 15 Leiden J. Intl. L. 553 (2002), discuss a range of views on the various risks of fragmentation. 155 As in the case of Van Alphen v. The Netherlands, where the partially dissenting judges inquired as to whether it was “permissible today for the Europe Convention on Human Rights to provide a lower level of protection than that which is recognized and accepted in other orga- nizations.” 156 M. Salomon, Global Responsibility for Human Rights 106 (Oxford U. Press 2007). See also her related discussion of disparate and contradictory trends in of international legal regimes and the need for international policy coherence; id., 150, 156. 157 Kingsbury et al., supra note 139, at 16. 158 There is a growing body of literature on the theme of accountability in the context of global governance and constitutionalism; see G. de Búrca & J. Scott ed., Law and New Governance in the EU and the US (Hart Publishing 2006). 159 On this theme as applied to the World Bank, see D. Clark, The World Bank and Human Rights: The Need for Greater Accountability, 15 Harv. Hum. Rights J. 205 (2002); S. Skogly, The Hu- man Rights Obligations of the World Bank and the International Monetary Fund (Cavendish Press 2001); D. Bradlow, The World Bank, the IMF and Human Rights, 6 Transnatl. L. & Contemp. Probs. 48–89 (1996); D. Bradlow & C. Grossman, Limited Mandates and Intertwined Problems: A New Challenge for the World Bank and the IMF, 17 Hum. Rights Q. (1995); D. Bradlow, The World Bank, the IMF and Human Rights, 6(1) Transnatl. L. & Contemp. Probs 48 (1996); M. Darrow, Between Light and Shadow: The World Bank, the IMF and International Human Rights Law (Hart Publishing 2003); W. van Genugten, P. Hunt, & S. Mathews, World Bank, IMF and Human Rights (Wolf Legal Publishers 2003). 160 Newell & Wheeler, supra note 39, at 7. The World Bank Legal Review150 altogether in development will significantly undermine accountability. That is, the potential to advance accountability for development or access to re- sources or basic services is difficult to advance in a context in which rights are not explicitly acknowledged. The identification of such gaps is symptom- atic of broader concerns that exist about accountability and legitimacy in the context of globalization, the expansion and scope of authority of multilateral organizations, and the increase in numbers of NGOs.161 Thus, human rights accountability may be difficult to locate and uphold where human rights law obligations are not integrated into development policies162 in a way that states—as donors or clients—can pursue development activities without sys- tematic assessments of the human rights consequences of these and without formal legal recourse where those consequences are negative in respect to both process and outcomes.163 Arguing for Coherence Based on Human Rights Obligations The trend of increasingly explicit recognition of human rights obligations and instruments may have positive potential for human rights protection in development. This suggestion is supported by the increased emphasis on in- ternational policy coherence, in particular, coherence based on states’ human rights obligations. Indeed, the UN Guiding Principles on Business and Hu- man Rights, adopted by states in the UN Human Rights Council, include a principle on ensuring policy coherence: “8. States should ensure that govern- mental departments, agencies, and other state-based institutions that shape business practices are aware of and observe the State’s human rights obliga- tions when fulfilling their respective mandates, including by providing them with relevant information, training and support.”164 This section assesses the value of coherence and regime interaction in international law in relation to human rights and development. It focuses on international human rights trea- ties165 to suggest how the pursuit of international legal coherence could be approached and why it might benefit development regimes. 161 R. Grant & R. Keohane, Accountability and Abuses of Power in World Politics, 99(1) Am. Pol. Science Rev. 29 (Feb. 2005). 162 This point does not, however, ignore other important forms of accountability, such as social accountability. Nor does it assume that legal accountability mechanisms are the sole or most effective means of ensuring that people can claim and realize their rights. 163 On this theme, see P. Twomey, Human Rights–Based Approaches to Development: Towards Accountability, in Economic, Social and Cultural Rights in Action 45–69 (M. A. Baderin & R. McCorquodale ed., Oxford U. Press 2007). 164 John Ruggie, Report of the Special Representative of the Secretary-General on the Issue of Human Rights and Transnational Corporations and Other Business Enterprises: Guiding Principles on Busi- ness and Human Rights: Implementing the United Nations “Protect, Respect and Remedy” Frame- work, A/HRC/17/31 21 (Mar. 2011). 165 In this it does not disregard the potential source of obligations in custom or general prin- ciples of law, but focuses on treaties as the most visible and clear source of such obligations for the purposes of the present discussion. For a more elaborate discussion of this argument, see S. McInerney-Lankford, International Financial Institutions and Human Rights: Select Per- spectives on Legal Obligations, in International Financial Institutions and International Law 239 Human Rights and Development 151 Principle 8 of the UN Guiding Principles on Business and Human Rights elaborates on the importance of both vertical and horizontal policy coherence based on government’s human rights obligations. “Vertical policy coherence entails States having the necessary policies, laws and processes to implement their international human rights law obligations. Horizontal policy coher- ence means supporting and equipping departments and agencies, at both the national and sub-national levels, that shape business practices . . . to be informed of and act in a manner compatible with the Governments’ human rights obligations.”166 Principles of international law may promote strategic regime interaction and advance policy coherence between human rights and development in rel- evant ways. For instance, the principle of systemic integration,167 derived from Article 31(3)(c) of the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties,168 states that in addition to the treaty’s context, “any relevant rules of international law ap- plicable in relations between parties” should be taken into account under the general rule of interpretation of treaties. This principle is, according to some, “the most influential principle in terms of reception of international law,”169 and one that could be used more generally to argue for taking relevant bind- ing human rights obligations into account in certain development contexts. In particular, this principle might support the integration of relevant human rights obligations at the levels of strategies, programs, processes, or projects as “relevant rules of international law applicable between the parties.” This (D. Bradlow & D. Hunter ed., Kluwer International 2010). 166 Guiding Principles, supra note 164, at 11–12. 167 C. McLachlan, The Principle of Systemic Integration and Article 31(3)(c) of the Vienna Convention, 54 ICLQ 279–320 (2005). 168 Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties (VCLT), UNTS Vol. 1155 (entered into force Jan. 27, 1980). 169 Forowicz, 13. Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties (VCLT), Article 31: General rule of interpretation: 1. A treaty shall be interpreted in good faith in accordance with the ordinary meaning to be given to the terms of the treaty in their context and in the light of its object and purpose. 2. The context for the purpose of the interpretation of a treaty shall comprise, in addi- tion to the text, including its preamble and annexes: a. Any agreement relating to the treaty which was made between all the parties in con- nexion with the conclusion of the treaty; b. Any instrument which was made by one or more parties in connexion with the conclu- sion of the treaty and accepted by the other parties as an instrument related to the treaty. 3. There shall be taken into account, together with the context: a. Any subsequent agreement between the parties regarding the interpretation of the treaty or the application of its provisions; b. Any subsequent practice in the application of the treaty which establishes the agree- ment of the parties regarding its interpretation; c. Any relevant rules of international law applicable in the relations between the parties. 4. A special meaning shall be given to a term if it is established that the parties so intended. The World Bank Legal Review152 would apply only when the human rights treaty in question was ratified by the state involved and would be delimited also by subject matter relevance. Countries are both parties to human rights treaties and members of devel- opment organizations, and what they do in each realm has potential relevance to the other.170 Without arguing for this principle as a prerequisite for regime interaction, the existence of parallel membership171 between the regimes gov- erning human rights and development is a factor in assessing the relevance of human rights to development and the relationship between their norms. Binding human rights treaty obligations could be relied upon substantively and in the interpretation of a range of development measures in areas cov- ered by a particular human rights treaty provision. In the case of ambiguity or conflict, a human rights treaty obligation and its accompanying interpretation and elaboration by the relevant expert treaty body could provide policy guid- ance grounded in the law. Human rights offer an established legal foundation upon which to base international policy coherence: The fact that both donors and partner countries have ratified the international human rights treaties provides a uniquely valuable reference point for harmonisation efforts. A mutually agreed, uni- versal normative framework already exists, supported not only by political commitment, but also by the force of legal obligation. As well, at the operational level, there is growing convergence in the integration of human rights in development.172 The foregoing does not deny the influence of cultural relativism, diver- gent interpretations of human rights norms, and differences among the social orders across countries and regions, which can be accentuated with respect to rights. In “a pluralist international society in which human rights are not pro- tected at all or only minimally protected the social basis for global administra- tive law based on individual rights is largely absent.”173 What is contended here is that the legal basis for integrating human rights into development, and possibly other spheres of international regulation, does exist in the shared hu- man rights treaty obligations of states. What are the practical benefits of such integration for development? 170 On the related question of the law binding international organization as subjects of inter- national law, the International Court of Justice (ICJ) has long established that such organiza- tions are “bound by any obligations incumbent upon them under general rules of interna- tional law, under their constitutions or under international agreements to which they are parties.” Interpretation of the Agreement of 25 March 1951 between WHO and Egypt, Advisory Opinion, 1980 ICJ Reports, at 89–90. 171 Young, supra note 1, at 94–96. 172 OECD DAC Human Rights Task Team, Human Rights and Aid Effectiveness, DAC Update 3 (Apr. 2007). 173 Kingsbury et al., supra note 139, at 46. Human Rights and Development 153 Coherence and Legal Accountability Some might argue that coherence is a benefit in and of itself and that it un- derpins the international rule of law and legal certainty upon which every specialized body of international law depends.174 This chapter suggests that pursuing such coherence based on the principle of systemic integration could ensure the consideration of human rights treaty obligations and thereby pro- mote legal accountability for human rights in development processes and outcomes. Strengthening accountability by framing development in terms of legal entitlements175 would help ensure that development benefits the poor- est and most vulnerable, thereby promoting poverty reduction goals too. An- choring relevant aspects of development regimes in applicable human rights treaty obligations could mitigate incoherence by providing a relatively clear legal and normative baseline for assessment. Thus, coherence around binding human rights treaty obligations would support states parties (whether as donors, partners, or merely members of development agencies and banks) upholding their human rights obligations and ensure accountability for human rights in development processes and outcomes. Such a renewed consideration of applicable legal norms could strengthen accountability more generally176 by reinforcing legal accountability in frameworks that are more usually the purview of broad policy commit- ments, programs, and processes than of treaties.177 Do No Harm/Do Good A more strategic engagement of development and human rights regimes might ensure that development policies and activities adapt to evolving in- ternational norms such as human rights.178 In particular, it would help ensure that states “do no harm” and that, at a minimum, states engaged in develop- ment bilaterally or through multilateral agencies consider their obligations and endeavor not to undermine human rights standards.179 That is, the in- tegration of relevant human rights standards based on international human rights law obligations could support the prevention and mitigation of undue 174 See supra notes 153 and 154. 175 P. Gready, Rights-Based Approaches to Development: What Is the Value-Added?, 18(6) Dev. in Practice 737 (Nov. 2008). 176 On the theme of accountability in globalized lawmaking and the emerging principles and requirements of global administrative law, see Kingsbury et al., supra note 139, at 44 –45 and 58–59. 177 International trade agreements and environmental treaties do feature somewhat more prom- inently in development policies; see World Bank OP 4.01—Environmental Assessment ( Jan. 1999), available at http://go.worldbank.org/RUEQVWD550. 178 Sureda, supra note 9, at 217. 179 This point is eloquently made by Andres Rigo Sureda, former deputy general counsel of the World Bank: “The IBRD is rightly concerned with its borrowers respecting the treaties that bind them in the course of its operations. In its work, there should not be any question that the IBRD is bound to respect them. [It] itself should not be instrumental in creating opportu- nities for the violation of human rights.” Supra note 9, at 218. http://go.worldbank.org/RUEQVWD550 The World Bank Legal Review154 harm, especially of a social and environmental nature. In this, human rights obligations, such as the obligation to respect, would serve as a minimum stan- dard against which development policies and activities could be assessed to ensure against harm in both processes and outcomes. An apposite example of such a standard emerges in the UN Guiding Prin- ciples on Business and Human Rights.180 Principle 13 states: The responsibility to respect human rights requires that business enterprises: a. Avoid causing or contributing to adverse human rights impacts through their own activities, and address such impacts when they occur; b. Seek to prevent or mitigate adverse human rights impacts that are directly linked to their operations, products or services by their business relationships, even if they have not contributed to those impacts. Although the principles are primarily an elaboration of business enter- prises’ responsibilities rather than state legal obligations, they offer concep- tual and practical guidance by analogy. The different regimes might benefit from interaction and mutual defini- tion. There may be potential for mutual reinforcement among norms derived from human rights and development regimes181 such that human rights ob- ligations of donors and partners could inform development policy and its monitoring and evaluation frameworks,182 or development cooperation activi- ties could advance the realization of human rights (particularly economic and social rights).183 For instance, one could argue that a state party’s obligations under Article 12 of the ICESCR, protecting the right to health,184 might be rele- 180 See Guiding Principles on Business and Human Rights, supra note 164; and UN OHCHR, Corpo- rate Responsibility to Respect Human Rights: An Interpretative Guide 15 –22 (advance unedited version, Nov. 2011). 181 See M. Robinson & P. Alston, The Challenges of Ensuring the Mutuality of Human Rights and Development Endeavours, in Human Rights and Development: Towards Mutual Reinforcement (M. Robinson & P. Alston ed., Oxford U. Press 2005). 182 The fact that the monitoring and internal reviews of the UN Development Programme (UNDP), World Bank, and International Monetary Fund (IMF) do not take the established system of international human rights monitoring into account is noted as a concern by P. Alston, Ships Passing in the Night: The Current State of the Human Rights and Development De- bate Seen through the Lens of the Millennium Development Goals, 27(3) Hum. Rights Q. 755, 814 (2005). 183 See an analogous argument on the potential for a positive role for a development agency (World Bank) to support the realization of the right to food. G. van Hoof & B. G. Tahzib, Supervision with Respect to the Right to Food and the Role of the World Bank, in International Law and Development 334 (Paul de Waart, Paul Peters, & Eric Denters ed., Martinus Nijhoff 1988). 184 Article 12 of the ICESCR provides: 1. The States Parties to the present Covenant recognize the right of everyone to the en- joyment of the highest attainable standard of physical and mental health. 2. The steps Human Rights and Development 155 vant to the design and implementation of a development project, program, or strategy in the health sector.185 In particular, Article 12 could inform both mini- mum standards for process and outcomes by reference to the core obligation to ensure minimum essential levels of the right to health.186 One could argue further that general comment 14, issued in 2000 by the Committee on Eco- nomic, Social, and Cultural Rights on the right to the highest attainable stan- dard of health, could provide relevant guidance to a state party engaged in development cooperation activities in the health sector.187 For instance, guid- ance could be drawn from the four dimensions established by the committee: availability, accessibility, acceptability, and quality.188 The right to health might inform a program’s focus on nondiscrimination and equality and the rights of the most vulnerable groups. It might also provide specificity in terms of both freedoms and entitlements, as well as precision in terms of more particular entitlements implied by the right, such as maternal and reproductive health; water; prevention, treatment, and control of diseases; and a healthy workplace and environment.189 One outcome of the regime interaction described above would be to facili- tate the adaptation of development to evolving international norms such as human rights. This would help “transform development priorities from being measured in macroeconomic terms by focusing on the needs and interests of specific human groups.”190 Or, to argue this point further, this would move development from a matter of needs and trade-offs to one of rights and obli- gations. In this way, a more explicit integration of rights would focus on poor people’s ability to realize the rights to resources and enhance accountability in development.191 At a less formal legal level, it can be argued that human rights to be taken by the States Parties to the present Covenant to achieve the full realization of this right shall include those necessary for: (a) The provision for the reduction of the stillbirth-rate and of infant mortality and for the healthy development of the child; (b) The improvement of all aspects of environ- mental and industrial hygiene; (c) The prevention, treatment and control of epidemic, endemic, occupational and other diseases; (d) The creation of conditions which would assure to all medical service and medical attention in the event of sickness. 185 Grover, supra note 10, paragraphs 24, 49. 186 Id., paragraph 19. 187 See Committee on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, General Comment No. 14, Sub- stantive Issues Arising in the Implementation of the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, The Right to the Highest Attainable Standard of Health (Article 12 of the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights), E/C.12/2000/4 (Aug. 11, 2000). 188 See also E. Reidel, The Human Right to Health: Conceptual Foundations, in Realizing the Right to Health vol. 3, 28–30 (M. Robinson & A. Clapham ed., Swiss Human Rights 2009). 189 Paul Hunt, Report of the Special Rapporteur on the Right of Everyone to the Enjoyment of the Highest Attainable Standard of Physical and Mental Health, E/CN.4/2003/58, paragraph 25 (Feb. 13, 2003). 190 M. Koskenniemi, Hegemonic Regimes, in Young, supra note 1, at 322. 191 Newell & Wheeler, supra note 39, at 1, place accountability at the intersection between rights and resources. The World Bank Legal Review156 principles such as participation, inclusion, and transparency in respect to regime interaction and in the structures and processes that govern develop- ment can promote accountability within it.192 Specificity and Technical Guidance In the context of development as a shared,193 stable, bounded structure of trea- ties with substantial and in some cases near-universal ratification,194 the human rights law framework includes a number of key strengths. These offer a le- gitimate195 and delimited legal and normative baseline founded on the volun- tarily undertaken commitments of states that bind them under international law. Human rights treaties are binding international agreements, and, like trade agreements or environment treaties, human rights treaties generate le- gally binding norms and enjoy high levels of ratification.196 However, human rights treaties predate many of these other treaties and have well-established bodies of interpretation and jurisprudence to support them. Beyond their nor- mative power and legally binding nature, such treaties introduce a measure of specificity with regard to substantive and procedural standards—their provi- sions have been the subject of extensive commentary through the interpreta- tions of treaty monitoring bodies,197 the individual complaints brought under those treaties,198 and, in the case of the regional human rights bodies, binding court rulings. In recent years, the UN human rights treaty bodies have enhanced the accuracy and consistency of interpretation by supporting the development of human rights indicators by the Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights (OHCHR).199 The framework adopted by the OHCHR offers method- 192 See, for example, Young, supra note 1, at 107. 193 AOPP, Principle 1, paragraph 40(1). 194 See, for example, the Convention on the Rights of the Child, which is ratified by all but three countries in the world (the United States, Somalia, and South Sudan); of those nonstate parties, the United States has signed the treaty and is, according to Article 18 of the VCLT, therefore obliged not to act against the object and purpose of the treaty. On the role and strengths of international human rights treaties, see B. Simma & P. Alston, The Sources of Hu- man Rights Law: Custom, Jus Cogens and General Principles, 12 Australian Yearbook of Intl. L. 81–108 (1992). 195 Grant & Keohane note that the standards of legitimacy against which power wielders can be held accountable derive from different sets of norms, and that legitimacy derives from conformity with human rights norms; supra note 161, at 35. 196 http://www2.ohchr.org/english/bodies/ratification/index.htm. 197 UN Human Rights Treaty Bodies, http://www2.ohchr.org/english/bodies/treaty/index.htm. 198 http://www2.ohchr.org/english/bodies/petitions/index.htm. Five of the human rights treaty bodies (CCPR, CERD, CAT, CEDAW, and CRPD) may, under particular circum- stances, consider individual complaints or communications from individuals. 199 This work was initiated in 2005 at the request of the intercommittee meeting of UN human rights treaty bodies to help it assess the use of statistical information in states parties’ reports in assessing the implementation of human rights. See Report on Indicators for Monitoring Com- pliance with International Human Rights Instruments, HRI/MC/2006/7; a report was issued in 2011 that applied the analysis to economic, social, and cultural rights (Report of the UN High Com- http://www2.ohchr.org/english/bodies/treaty/index.htm http://www2.ohchr.org/english/bodies/petitions/index.htm http://www2.ohchr.org/english/bodies/ratification/index.htm Human Rights and Development 157 ological, institutional, and practical considerations for the effective use of hu- man rights indicators. The OHCHR has developed a series of indicators for approximately 12 human rights, covering economic, social, and cultural rights as well as civil and political rights.200 These indicators may be of particular use for development in supporting the measurement of economic, social, and cultural rights by charting progress, stagnation, and retrogression, as well as patterns of discrimination and marginalization.201 Indeed, beyond being posi- tively received and used within the UN system, other agencies and human rights bodies,202 and NGOs, the indicators have been employed by certain governments in national development plans. Connected with the advances in empirical approaches and measurement methodology on human rights indicators and benchmarks, there is a grow- ing body of work on human rights impact assessment (HRIA).203 HRIAs have been developed across a range of sectors, supporting the case for both the feasibility of bringing human rights law to bear in other areas of law and the possibility of generating concreteness and specificity to back the normative underpinning of human rights. In particular, such assessments advance the possibility of identifying rights and duties in a range of contexts and help specify both the human rights claims of rights holders and the corresponding human rights obligations of duty bearers. Such assessment can also identify the immediate, underlying, and structural causes of nonrealization of human rights, as well as offer recommendations on mitigation and approaches for redress,204 monitoring, and evaluation. Conclusions As suggested above, the fragmentation of international law may be as en- demic as it is pervasive, and it may even constitute a semideliberate state of affairs. The specificity of roles of different international regimes and their in- stitutions should be respected for legal, technical, and political reasons; this may be required to afford institutions a necessary measure of flexibility and allow them to leverage their comparative advantages in their respective fields of competence. A host of legal challenges attendant on a project of pursuing missioner on Human Rights, E/2011/90). See http://www.ohchr.org/EN/Issues/Indicators /Pages/documents.aspx. 200 Report on Monitoring and Promoting the Implementation of Human Rights, HRI/MC/2008/3. 201 Report of the UN High Commissioner on Human Rights, E/2011/90, paragraphs 23–24. 202 For example, the European Union Fundamental Rights Agency. Also relevant is the work on human rights benchmarks commissioned by the EU Parliament Subcommittee, Briefing Paper: Human Rights Benchmarks for EU External Policy, EXPO/B/DROI/2011/15, available at http://www.europarl.europa.eu/committees/fr/studiesdownload.html?languageDocume nt=EN&file=67511. 203 See, for example, S. Walker, The Future of Human Rights Impact Assessments of Trade Agreements (Intersentia 2009). 204 Grover, supra note 10, paragraph 22. http://www.ohchr.org/EN/Issues/Indicators/Pages/documents.aspx http://www.ohchr.org/EN/Issues/Indicators/Pages/documents.aspx http://www.europarl.europa.eu/committees/fr/studiesdownload.html?languageDocument=EN&file=67511 http://www.europarl.europa.eu/committees/fr/studiesdownload.html?languageDocument=EN&file=67511 The World Bank Legal Review158 coherence have been expertly documented by the ILC Study Group, among others. These include the absence of a hierarchy among norms;205 the fact that the Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties does not provide clear guidance on the meaning of “systemic integration” or on how to reconcile conflicting norms; and the lack of an international legislature or appeals court to resolve conflicts around norms and their interpretation. The questions and challenges arising from international bodies reviewing the actions of other international organizations are myriad,206 and their complexity is evident in the EU-Europe- an Convention on Human Rights context,207 with no sense that they would be any less fractious or challenging in the context of human rights agencies and development organizations. The general limits on competences and resourc- es of various international agencies may be heightened in respect to human rights obligations when institutions operate subject to political prohibitions208 that have historically been interpreted to bar human rights considerations.209 At a technical level, the body of knowledge on human rights measure- ment methodology, although growing, is incomplete despite significant prog- ress in areas such as human rights impact assessments and human rights indi- cators. Human rights assessment itself is controversial: it is attended by risks of politicization, annexation, and externalization and, many argue, impossible to undertake in a completely neutral or objective manner. Resources are a relevant consideration here as well: HRIAs are costly and time-consuming, and monitoring and implementation require substantial institutional commit- ments and large amounts of data. For development agencies that do not operate from a normative base and do not fulfill an enforcement role with respect to human rights norms, the fact that the instrumental case for human rights in development has yet to be per- suasively established presents an additional challenge. That is, although risk- based arguments related to “do no harm” can be made, the empirical basis for arguing that integrating human rights increases development effectiveness is less clear. This is compounded by the relatively small number of quality hu- man rights indicators developed, the dearth of human rights data (especially 205 ILC Study Group, supra note 42, at paragraph 31. 206 Kingsbury et al., supra note 139, at 45. 207 See, for example, C. Costello, The Bosphorus Ruling of the European Court of Human Rights: Fundamental Rights and Blurred Boundaries in Europe, 6(1) Hum. Rights L. Rev. 87–130 (2006); T. Lock, EU Accession to the ECHR: Implications for the Judicial Review in Strasbourg, 35 Euro- pean L. Rev. 777 (2010). 208 For example, IRBD Articles of Agreement, Article IV, Section 10, and Article III, Section 5 (Dec. 27, 1945), available at http://siteresources.worldbank.org/EXTABOUTUS/Resources /ibrd-articlesofagreement.pdf. Similar provisions exist in the constituent instruments of a number of other development banks, such as the Inter-American Development Bank and the African Development Bank. 209 Ibrahim Shihata, The World Bank and Human Rights, in The World Bank in a Changing World Selected Essays and Lectures vol. 2, 567 (Martinus Nijhoff 1991); similarly, see Ibrahim Shihata, Human Rights and International Financial Institutions, in id., 553. http://siteresources.worldbank.org/EXTABOUTUS/Resources/ibrd-articlesofagreement.pdf http://siteresources.worldbank.org/EXTABOUTUS/Resources/ibrd-articlesofagreement.pdf Human Rights and Development 159 in developing countries), and the difficulty of establishing causation or attri- bution between human rights requirements and development outcomes. Nevertheless, despite the legal, political, and practical challenges of argu- ing for the integration of human rights obligations into development regimes, and despite the elusive nature of coherence in the international legal system, the core relevance of human rights to development must be recognized, and the legal treaty obligations underpinning human rights are one reason to do so. These treaty obligations form part of the body of evolving international norms that have practical relevance and legal pertinence for development re- gimes such that the latter should interact with, and adapt to, them. Interaction between human rights and development regimes could be mutually benefi- cial, potentially strengthening aspects of each regime. At the very least, hu- man rights should not be ignored in development frameworks, in respect of a minimum no-harm threshold. The overall benefit of such interaction and systemic integration would be enhanced by accountability for human rights in development, at least at the macrolevel of regimes, through a more formal type of “hierarchical, supervisory, accountability” system210 and through alter- native accountability models based on a more “dynamic experimentalist vision of benchmarking, borrowing, innovating, monitoring and mutual learning.”211 Human rights and development are inextricably interwoven, but their governing frameworks and regimes have remained largely separate. A grow- ing, but as yet uneven, integration of human rights into development re- gimes is occurring, and there is some evidence of growing recognition of the relevance of human rights treaty obligations in development regimes. This trend signals—despite the prevailing distinctions, fragmentation, and poten- tial conflict—evidence of the possibility for strategic links between human rights and development regimes and the political will to forge them. The trend also augurs well for the possibility of mutually beneficial norm defini- tion through regime interaction at the formal legal level in ways that both avoid harm and do good. 210 Kingsbury et al., supra note 139, at 58, drawing on Grant & Keohane, Accountability and Abuses of Power in World Politics, IILJ Working Paper 2004/7, at 14. 211 Kingsbury et al., supra note 139, at 58, drawing on Grant & Keohane, supra note 211. 161 Legal Transplantation and Legal Development in Transitional China Chenguang Wang China claims that its legal system and the rule of law it intends to build have strong Chinese characteristics distinct from those in the Western world and closely associated with the Chinese socialist political system and social envi- ronment.1 There is no doubt that China’s legal system and its commitment to building a rule of law have had a great effect on the nation’s social and economic development; the Chinese economic boom could not have been achieved without a functional legal system compatible with international and foreign legal practices. In this regard, legal transplantation was a useful tool in the establishment of the Chinese legal system.2 This chapter does not examine the credibility of China’s legal system, but rather proposes that the Chinese legal system has borrowed elements from other legal systems in order to pro- mote its unique market economy reform and social transition in the context of globalization. Legal Transplantation Is a Typical Aspect of Legal Development A function of comparative law is to better understand and improve national legislative work through comparison with foreign and internal legal systems.3 Comparison of different legal systems and the adoption of foreign law on the basis of such comparison or military occupation are established practices in The author is grateful for Dr. Ju Chengwei’s assistance in collecting materials and offering valuable comments on the draft and also for Mr. Hassane Cissé’s insightful comments on the paper. 1 Wu Bangguo, chairman of the National People’s Congress of China, has emphasized that the Chinese legal system embodies Chinese socialist characteristics. In 2011, he announced that “China has established a legal system with Chinese characteristics” and that “we do not use the legal systems in some Western countries as models to cast China’s legal system with Chinese characteristics.” He further indicated that “we are not going to make those laws which exist in foreign systems but do not fit into the Chinese social environment and reality.” Wu Bangguo, Annual Report of the National People’s Congress’ Work of 2011, available at http:// english.gov.cn/2008-03/15/content_921044.htm. 2 Wu Bangguo has said that “we should also learn from foreign experiences in the law making process and adopt those experiences useful to us.” Id. 3 Shen Zongling, On Comparative Law 50–51 (Peking U. Press 1998); Konrad Zweigert & Kein Kötz, Introduction to Comparative Law 17 (Oxford U. Press 1998); Alan Watson, Society & Legal Change 141 (Scottish Academic Press 1977); Rudolf B. Schlesinger, Hans W. Baade, Peter E. Herzog, & Mirjan R. Damaska, Comparative Law: Cases-Text-Materials 9 (5th ed., West Press 1998). http://english.gov.cn/2008-03/15/content_921044.htm http://english.gov.cn/2008-03/15/content_921044.htm The World Bank Legal Review162 history. Legal transplantation—the movement of laws and legal institutions from one state to another—is central to the study of comparative and inter- national law.4 In the midst of globalization, legal transplantation has become more frequent and common. The purposes of legal transplantation are not confined to better understanding and improving national legal systems; le- gal transplantation also promotes the convergence, at least in some fields of law, of different national laws in the global arena. Legal transplantation can be used to improve a national legal system and to promote a uniform global legal framework in the areas of international trade, environmental protection, antiterrorism, international peace, and the protection of human rights. The concept of legal transplantation is an ancient one. Solon of Athens studied laws of other Greek city-states as a basis for social reform. Aristotle studied more than 150 constitutions of other cities to compose Politics. It is said that the XII Tables, the first Roman code, incorporated references to ancient Greek city-states.5 While the Roman Empire declined, the conquering German tribes retained the Roman legal tradition.6 During the Renaissance and the Industrial Revolution, the use of comparative law became increasingly signifi- cant in the rising nation-states. Even the “original” Western legal systems were affected by foreign law: French and German legal systems are based on the Roman legal tradition;7 Anglo-American law is also influenced by civil law.8 In the 19th and early 20th centuries, the emergence of the global market and colonization brought these legal systems to Africa, Asia, and Latin America.9 After World War II, globalization engulfed the world. The US model of law and development introduced “ideal” legal models to the newly indepen- dent states.10 Despite the failure of the first law and development movement, 4 Jonathan M. Miller, A Typology of Legal Transplants: Using Sociology, Legal History and Argentine Examples to Explain the Transplant Process, 51 Am. J. Comp. L. 839 (2003). 5 René David & John E. C. Brierley, Major Legal Systems in the World Today: An Introduction to the Comparative Study of Law 1–2 (2d ed., Stevens & Sons, 1978); Andrew Borkowski, Textbook on Roman Law 26 (Blackstone Press Limited 1994). 6 Alan Watson, The Evolution of Law 77–92 ( Johns Hopkins U. Press 1985); M. H. Hoeflich, Law, Society and Reception: The Vision of Alan Watson 85 Mich. L. Rev. 1086 (1987). 7 John Henry Merryman, The Civil Law Tradition: An Introduction to the Legal Systems of Western Europe and Latin America 10 (2d ed., Stanford U. Press 1985). 8 Watson demonstrates that Commentaries on the Laws of England, by William Blackstone, the founder of English law, was based on a reference to Dutch scholar Dionysius Gothofredus’s (1549–1622) interpretation of the Institutes of Justinian. English and American conflicts of law referred to Praelectines Iuris Vivilis et Hodienrni by Ulrich Huber, a Dutch scholar. See Alan Watson, Legal Transplants: An Approach to Comparative Law 94, 109–110 (U. Georgia Press 1993). Jerome Frank points out that “[c]ivil law tradition has many impacts on common law.” He expounds on the far-reaching but often neglected impacts of civil law tradition on Ameri- can common law in the areas of the constitution, conflicts of law, legal interpretation, and judicial procedure: “The influences of civil law on common law are legion. Many of them doubtlessly can’t be detected.” Jerome Frank, Civil Law Influences on the Common Law: Some Reflections on “Comparative” and “Contrastive” Law, 104 U. Penn. L. Rev. 888 (1956). 9 David & Brierley, supra note 5, at 69–73; and Shen, supra note 3, at 75–77. 10 Daniel Berkowitz, Katharina Pistor, & Jean-Francois Richard, The Transplant Effect, 51 Am. J. Comp. L. 163 (2003). Legal Transplantation and Legal Development in Transitional China 163 subsequent movements emerged with different theoretical foundations and strategic emphases.11 The collapse of the former Soviet Union and the social- ist bloc encouraged the transplantation of the European and American legal model to East European and former Soviet Union countries as they tried to restructure their legal systems.12 In today’s world, no national legal system can be separated entirely from foreign and international law. Many comparative law scholars emphasize the importance of legal trans- plantation in legal and social development. Orucu states that “the movement of legal institutions and ideas is trans-border and such transmigration is a natural phase in legal development. This is both a historical and present fact and the future will see more of it.”13 He further asserts, “It is a truism that the amount of innovation in law is small and borrowing and imitation is of central importance in understanding the course of legal change.”14 Sacco holds that “borrowing and imitation is therefore of central importance to understanding the course of legal change.”15 Watson points out that direct transplants of legal systems have proliferated in human history and constitute the most important forces for legal development.16 Watson questions Savigny’s volksgeist (popu- lar consciousness), the Marxist theory of economic determinacy, and Jhering’s and Pound’s theory of the sociology of law. He contends that the relation between law and society is more remote than people think and that legal rules are not designed for the particular society in which they operate.17 Not all scholars recognize the important role of legal transplantation in legal development. Montesquieu asserts that “the political and civil laws of each nation ought to be only the particular cases in which this human rea- son is applied. They should be adapted in such a manner to the people for whom they are framed that it should be a great chance if those of one nation 11 David M. Trubek, Law and Development in a Time of Multiple Visions: The Challenge of the New Developmental State, presentation at Renmin University Law School, available at http:// www.law.ruc.edu.cn/Article/ShowAritcle.asp?ArticleID=11151. Trubek states, “In the first moment, law was seen as a strong tool to be used by the state to shape and guide behavior. In the second it was promoted as a shield against state intervention and a framework for pri- vate transactions.” The third moment is a new type of law and development in developing countries, exemplified by China and Brazil, which show “signs of wanting to move beyond neo-liberalism without simply trying to return to the developmental state of the 1950s and 1960s. . . . The new theories stress the idea that policies must be constructed through experi- mentation and public-private collaboration and tailored to the needs of specific industries and regions, . . . [and] suggest the need for variation within each nation as well as among them.” 12 Daniel Berkowitz, Katharina Pistor, & Jean-Francois Richard, Economic Development, Legality and the Transplant Effect, 47 European Eco. Rev. 166 (2003). 13 Esin Orucu, Law as Transposition, 51 Intl. Comp. L. Q. 205 (Apr. 2002). 14 Id., at 206. 15 Rodolfo Sacco, Legal Formants: A Dynamic Approach to Comparative Law, 39 Am. J. Comp. L. 394 (1991). 16 Watson, supra note 3, at 95. 17 Watson, supra note 6 at 8. http://www.law.ruc.edu.cn/Article/ShowAritcle.asp?ArticleID=11151 http://www.law.ruc.edu.cn/Article/ShowAritcle.asp?ArticleID=11151 The World Bank Legal Review164 suit another.”18 Savigny advocates volksgeist and theoretically rules out the feasibility of legal transplantation. In the contemporary field of comparative law, Kahn-Freund and Legrand represent the opposite theory, which objects to the possibility of legal transplantation. They hold that transplantation is impossible due to ingrained differences in the systems involved—transplan- tation does not occur at all: the product of moving a rule elsewhere is always something else, “not the same rule.”19 In recent years, both these absolutist visions have long collapsed into a middle ground, densely populated by authors who reject both the sunny aspects of Watson’s world of ever-flourishing transplants and Le- grand’s rejection of that vision. Much of the study has followed a culturalist path, under which outmoded legal formalism was re- placed by realist, socio-politico-cultural theories that consider law as a living social construct. Here, legal culture was offered as a key determinant of the viability of transplantation; complete isolation- ism and hermeneutical closeness were replaced by a vision of law as rooted in its cultural/social frameworks, but also amenable to vari- ous influences, among them foreign ones.20 Even those who assert that legal transplantation is the normal path of le- gal development, such as Watson, cannot refute the effects of national spirit, domestic economic and social foundations, and distinct culture, religion, and political factors on legal development. Watson quotes Engels’ statement that “in a modern state, law must not only correspond to the general economic position and be its expression, but must also be an expression which is consis- tent in itself, and which does not, owing to inner contradictions, look glaringly inconsistent.”21 Watson believes that these social factors are the cause of the transplantation of various forms of legal rules.22 In the post–Cold War world, ideological barriers for legal transplantation may seem insignificant and legal transplantation may appear to be a common phenomenon. But legal systems are based on the foundation of democracy, human rights, and a market economy and have enforced the impulse for ex- portation or transportation. Developing and transitional countries with newly developed market economies have introduced foreign laws in response to the pressures of economic development, democratization, and globalization. “To be in line with international conventions” is the accepted practice in the process of globalization, which encourages convergence or harmonization of legal systems in the areas of economic transactions, cultural exchanges, en- 18 Baron de Montesquieu, The Spirit of Laws vol.1, 6 (Cosimo Inc. 2007). 19 Margit Cohn, Legal Transplant Chronicles: The Evolution of Unreasonableness and Proportionality Review of the Administration in the United Kingdom, 58 Am. J. Comp. L. 586 (2010). 20 Id., at 587–88. 21 Watson, supra note 3. 22 Watson, supra note 6, at 97. Legal Transplantation and Legal Development in Transitional China 165 vironmental protection, international peace, and some public law fields. The formation of a common market and the wide acceptance of universal values provide a solid foundation for legal convergence and harmonization. The World Bank, the Asian Development Bank, and various foundations that sup- port economic and social development in developing and transitional coun- tries often require the reform of legal systems and the establishment of the rule of law as prerequisites for providing funds and other assistance. This obliga- tion further promotes legal transplants from developed countries to develop- ing countries. “However, the economic development, democratization, and globalization have today so sharply increased the number of legal transplants that at least in developing countries, most major legislation now has a foreign component.”23 The common trajectory of legal transplants is from developed and international legal regimes to developing countries. Thus, from both historical and practical perspectives, legal transplants are a common form of legal development. With the irresistible trend of globaliza- tion, the role of legal transplantation becomes ever more significant. Typology of Legal Transplants The transplantation debate continues, on issues of form, basic conditions, ef- fects, function, compatibility, and implementation. There is little true consen- sus on the typology of and basic conditions for legal transplantation. In practice, governments of different countries adopt different approaches toward legal transplantation because of practical concerns about national sov- ereignty, culture, history, ideology, and social system. Support or disapproval, toleration or rejection, wholesale or selective acceptance, uncritical or flexible adoption of different types of law—legal transplantation takes diversified and multidimensional forms. Moreover, the social, economic, and institutional con- texts often differ remarkably between the countries of origin and of transplant, creating fundamentally different conditions for effectuating the imported le- gal order in the latter. Transplant countries therefore are likely to suffer from the transplant effect, that is, the mismatch between preexisting conditions and institutions and transplanted law, which weakens the effectiveness of the im- ported legal order.24 Although Su Li’s concept of “indigenous legal resources” explains the mismatch problems from the Chinese perspective,25 an examina- tion of the typology of and basic conditions for legal transplantation is in order. Watson divides voluntary legal transplantation into different types: • The transplantation of original law into an uncivilized area by massive immigration 23 Miller, supra note 4. 24 Berkowitz, Pistor, & Richard, supra note 10, at 171. 25 Su Li, The Rule of Law and Its Indigenous Resources (China U. of Political Science & Law Press 2004). The World Bank Legal Review166 • The transplantation of original law into a civilized area • The voluntary acceptance of another nation’s law by the native people In addition, there are other types, such as imposed acceptance, selective adoption, intrusion, filtration, and tacit acceptance. Watson believes that both the type and scale of transplantation vary and that, without specific study of individual cases, categorization has little value and cannot bring new ideas to comparative study.26 Although legal transplantation is a normal form of legal development, it is by no means the only form. A particular social environment and country-specific factors are the major determinants of the development of a legal system. The necessity for and inevitability of revision, adaption, and natu- ralization of transplanted rules by the recipient country cannot be overlooked. Miller uses motives of legal transplantation to categorize its types. This categorization helps explain the internal impetus for legal transplantation in China. Miller believes that there are four types of legal transplantation: • The cost-saving transplant • The externally dictated transplant • The entrepreneurial transplant • The legitimacy-generating transplant27 This typology shifts the focus of transplantation from the donor’s per- spective to the recipient’s perspective. In practice, “many transplants are a mix of the four types, and one rarely encounters a type in pure form.”28 The Cost-Saving Transplant Implemented to save time and costly experimentation, a cost-saving trans- plantation “involves a drafter who when confronted with a new problem pulls a solution from elsewhere off the shelf of the library to save having to think up an original solution.”29 This type of transplantation has the benefit of speed, convenience, and direct application. However, it must be supplemented by a functional and systematic approach that is “the starting point and basis of all comparative law and that different legal systems can be compared only if they solve the same factual problem, satisfying the requirement in adequate legal regulation.”30 In the cost-saving approach, the prospective laws and mechan- ics to be transplanted are analyzed and selected after it has been determined 26 Watson, supra note 6, at 29–30. 27 Miller, supra note 4, at 842. 28 Id. 29 Miller, supra note 4, at 845. 30 Zweigert & Kötz, supra note 3, at 34; see also Jeffrey L. Dunoff & Joel P. Trachtman, Ruling the World? Constitutionalism, International Law, and Global Governance, in Constitutionalism, In- ternational Law and Global Governance 9 ( Jeffrey Dunoff ed., Cambridge U. Press 2009); Djalil Kiekbaev, Comparative Law: Method, Science or Educational Discipline? 7.3 Electronic J. Comp. L. (Sep. 2003), available at http://www.ejcl.org/73/art73-2.html. http://www.ejcl.org/73/art73-2.html Legal Transplantation and Legal Development in Transitional China 167 that both the donor and the recipient face similar social problems capable of being solved by the transplanted rules, and that the transplanted rules and mechanics will function in the same manner in both countries. Basing the de- cision purely on function is not sufficient because social environments may differ substantially, rendering the transplant a failure. This approach poses difficulties that make a complete checklist for comprehensive analysis of func- tion and social factors unrealistic.31 China adopted this approach. It “pays attention to draw ‘international ex- perience’ in the process [of] drafting important laws and regulations, namely, comparing with the relevant foreign and international laws.”32 For example, in the initial stage of “opening to the outside,” China had no experience in the area of foreign investment. To attract foreign investment and cooperation, the Chinese legislature reviewed laws relating to joint ventures and foreign investment from more than 20 countries. It borrowed directly from foreign and international experience in drafting its first law, the Sino-Foreign Equity Joint Venture Law, and thus laid the legal foundation for attracting foreign investment.33 To meet the needs of the increasing volume of foreign trade, the legislature has applied the United Nations Convention on Contracts for the International Sale of Goods to cases of international trade involving Chi- nese parties. In the areas relating to market formation and transaction, such as property, intellectual property rights, securities, companies, and bankruptcy, the legislature has also borrowed from foreign experience. This practice has become a conventional and regular step in China’s legislative process—the legislature sends staff and experts to other countries for field study or to col- lect similar laws for further research and adoption.34 By using this cost-saving transplant model, China has implemented laws based on foreign and interna- tional laws and mechanics to foster economic development. The Externally Dictated Transplant “Externally dictated transplants have become ubiquitous, particularly in developing countries. This kind of transplantation may involve a foreign individual, entity, or government that indicates the adoption of a legal model as a condition for doing business or for allowing the country a measure of political autonomy.”35 In the era of colonialism, a typical way to effect legal 31 Dunoff & Trachtman, id. 32 Shen, supra note 3, at 52. 33 Zhao Xin & Zhang Li, Deng Xiaoping on Sino-Foreign Equity Joint Venture Laws: A Political Declaration, Procuratorial Daily (Sep. 9, 2009). 34 Li Lin, Thirty Years of Reform & Open Policy and China’s Legislative Development, 7(2) Beijing Union U. Rev.—Social Science, 8–10 (2009). See also the civil law section of Comparison of Ar- ticles of Contract Law of the PRC with Relevant Foreign Contract Rules (Legislative Affairs Com- mission of the National People’s Congress ed., Law Press 1999). This detailed comparison indicates clearly that, in the process of drafting this statute, the legislative body conducted systematic and detailed comparisons and borrowed from successful foreign practices. 35 Miller, supra note 4, at 847. The World Bank Legal Review168 transplantation was to dictate acceptance of foreign law. In the contempo- rary world, adoption dictated by military occupation or colonization is rare, although adoption in developing counties dictated by other means, such as economic or diplomatic pressure, is not uncommon. China accepted certain unfavorable rules and conditions imposed by powerful trading partners in the process of negotiating for its membership in international organizations.36 Facing an established international market and regulatory regimes, China had to comply with externally imposed requirements and standards, includ- ing inspections and reviews by foreign agencies. To participate in the global market and export China-made products, China had little choice. Because of the pressure of this model, a recipient country often becomes the victim of economic, political, ideological, and diplomatic confrontation while reflecting the intrinsic demand for globalization and harmonization of the international legal framework; this type of legal transplantation is very common. The Entrepreneurial Transplant This model refers to individuals and groups who reap benefits from investing in, learning about, and encouraging local adoption of a foreign legal system. Its success depends on an exporter willing to provide capital and an importer interested in the import, each side guided by what it might gain domestically by operating internationally.37 In tandem with China’s opening to the outside and economic development, economic entities ranging from large state-owned enterprises to small private companies want to participate in international in- vestment and trade, resulting in direct contact with foreign companies and acceptance of foreign rules. For example, all Chinese companies (both state owned and private) must follow foreign rules when they intend to participate in a foreign securities market. Some enterprises directly apply foreign com- modity standards or labor standards in order to export their products to par- ticular countries. Products with quality below the standards of the importing country have no chance of entering the market; labor safety standards (such as safety protection and work environment) below a legal requirement in the importing country may result in the blockade and boycott of the exported products. Some scholars claim that legal transplantation through private ac- tors, by borrowing law through private contracting, has formed another type of transplantation. Through the channel of contracting, private transactors “smuggle” law across borders.38 As a large export-oriented trading country, 36 Pitman B. Potter, Globalization and Economic Regulation in China: Selective Adaptation of Global- ized Norms and Practices, 2 Wash. U. Global Studies L. Rev. 121–25 (2003). Potter analyzes the demands for China to adopt the principles of transparency, uniformity, national treatment, nondiscrimination, and compatibility with WTO rules, as well as the demands for certain rules and mechanics in the areas of trade, service, intellectual property rights, foreign ex- changes, customs, independent courts, and dispute settlement. 37 Miller, supra note 4, at 849–50. 38 Li-Wen Lin, Legal Transplants through Private Contracting: Codes of Vendor Conduct in Global Supply Chains as an Example, 57 Am. J. Comp. L. 713 –14 (2009). Legal Transplantation and Legal Development in Transitional China 169 China has implemented this model of legal transplantation through private economic and cultural exchanges. The Legitimacy-Generating Transplant This model refers to the process of consciously emulating the most prestigious foreign legal systems. Developing countries tend to regard the legal orders in developed countries as models to be copied. The wide acceptance in develop- ing countries of the doctrine and mechanics of the separation of powers and an independent judiciary, which are deemed as legitimate legal orders by the people just coming out of dictatorship, is an example.39 Different legal systems have their respective levels of prestige. “A country’s legal family is a significant determinant of the effectiveness of its legal system. Countries belonging to the English common law family have the most investor- friendly laws, French and German civil law countries have the least investor- friendly laws, and the Scandinavian countries fall somewhere between.”40 The US securities market is widely regarded as a prestigious legal regime because of its efficiency, flexibility, and security. In the process of drafting its securities laws and building its securities market, China turned to the US model. Similar borrowing and acceptance occurred in the areas of companies, insurance, an- titrust, banking, and accounting. Despite the fact that the US securities market was hit hard by the worldwide financial crisis, because of its critical role and function in the international securities market, its legal regime is still regarded by many countries as the most prestigious legal model, even though this model may harbor potential risks, such as financial bubbles and speculation. These four models focus on the motives and purposes of legal transplan- tation. A pure form of any one model is rare in practice, and a mix of the four is common.41 This mix will take different forms. For example, although China employs all these transplantation models, its incremental approach, the stability required by social transition, the national independence asserted by China in the international community, and its unique historical and social backgrounds constitute a unique Chinese environment of legal development that is distinct from those in other transitional and developing countries. Legal transplantation in China may have created a new model, positioned within a legal framework underpinned by socialism, based on the Chinese so- cial environment, and developed to explore the possibilities of a Chinese social- ist market economy and the Chinese socialist rule of law. Legal transplantation is an effective instrument to promote a legal system with Chinese characteris- tics that mixes transplantation models based on rational and active selection. 39 Id. 40 Berkowitz, Pistor, & Richard, supra note 10, at 166. 41 Miller, supra note 4, at 842. The World Bank Legal Review170 Conditions for a Successful Legal Transplant Simply establishing a typology of transplantation does not, of course, guaran- tee the success of legal transplantation. No matter what type of transplantation is employed, the process may end in failure or with setbacks. The failure of the first law-and-development movement triggered reexamination of the concept. Trubek and Galanter offered the first critique. In 1974, they asserted that the movement was dead because of excessive dependence on the governments of newly independent states and the one-sided intention of American schol- ars and lawyers to bring the legal order of developed countries to new states without considering the social conditions of the recipient countries.42 The sec- ond wave of the law-and-development movement was initiated by neoliberal- ism and the free market doctrine espoused by Ronald Reagan and Margaret Thatcher. This new round took the rule of law as its banner; democracy, free market doctrine, and liberalism as its theoretical foundation; and the Wash- ington Consensus as its guiding principle. The collapse of the socialist bloc headed by the Soviet Union cleared the way for the introduction of American and European legal systems into Russia and East European countries. But to a great extent, the results have not been satisfactory. The global financial crisis delivered a heavy blow to the theory and strategy of law and development. As a result, scholars question the credibility of the legal transplants in this mode and wonder how to guarantee the success of a legal transplantation, and how to use legal transplantation to achieve positive social effects. The success of a legal transplant does not depend exclusively on the choices of laws to transplant, on the system selected as the model, or on the faithful introduction of an entire system. No less important to success are the conditions for transplants in the recipient country. These conditions may already exist or may have to be created to ensure that a transplant is ac- cepted. These conditions include internal demand for the transplant and the local environment, such as relevant institutions, procedures, and social factors that promote and implement the transplanted laws and systems.43 A friendly environment for transplanted laws is one in which social and popular atti- tudes favor acceptance of the transplant, and in which there exists the capacity to absorb the transplant and the ability to resolve possible conflicts between the transplanted law and indigenous law and customs.44 If these conditions are absent or incomplete, no matter how magnificent the intention behind the transplant or how well designed it is, its final result will be disappointing. In the past 30 years, as China has faced numerous challenges in the tran- sition from a planned economy to a market economy, it has experienced an astonishing economic boom and rapid changes in its social structure. The 42 David Trubek & Marc Galanter, Scholars in Self-Estrangement: Some Reflections on the Crisis in Law and Development Studies in the United States, 14 Wis. L. Rev. 1062 (1974). 43 Berkowitz, Pistor, & Richard, supra note 10, at 179. 44 Zhang Jianyuan, Symptoms and Diagnosis of Legal Transplantation—Taking HIV Legal Policy as a Case for Study, 4 Ideological Front (2010). Legal Transplantation and Legal Development in Transitional China 171 decisive factor for such change has been the strong desire, embraced by the populace, the government, and the party in power, to build a “strong mod- ernized country” and to elevate living standards. The Cultural Revolution brought the Chinese economy to the edge of bankruptcy; under the planned economy commodities were in short supply and living standards remained at a very low level. The populace concluded that in the wake of the Cultural Revolution there was a need to “shift the working focus to socialist modern- ization and economic construction”45 and to improve living standards. Based on a strong consensus, the policy and practice of borrowing, introducing, and transplanting foreign and international law and legal systems triumphed. De- spite different views regarding choices and modes of transplantation, consen- sus to borrow foreign and international laws was achieved and maintained. By rationally borrowing and transplanting foreign laws to constitute a new legal system that pushes social reform and maintains the open-door policy, China has turned onto a new road. In regard to basic conditions for a successful transplant, China faces a complicated situation. First, as to the institutions and mechanisms that could facilitate transplantation, the existing apparatus, such as law enforcement agencies and judicial organs, has traditional ways of operating that are rife with defects and loopholes and often incompatible with newly transplanted law or mechanisms. When China introduced contracts as a means for market transactions, for example, organs such as the State Administration for Indus- try and Commerce still had the mind-set of a planned economy and exercised their control over business contracts by requiring them to be registered with the administration. Second, legal consciousness in China may still lag behind the laws that are being introduced. Although China has made an effort to build a legal system and promote the rule of law, the law is not regarded as the predominant norm in Chinese society, and the legal system and apparatus are not considered the primary means for constructing a new social structure or solving social problems. The Communist Party and state policies (or even the decisions of individual leaders) continue to play more significant roles than the law. In the areas of rural economic reform and state-owned enter- prise reform, policy is more effective and timely than law.46 Law is often used to enforce or institutionalize policy. In this regard, social and legal conditions are not sufficient for newly introduced laws that cannot have immediate le- gal effects without policy support. Finally, an inadequate legal consciousness creates hurdles to acceptance and implementation of introduced laws and mechanisms. 45 The Communiqué of the Third Plenary Session of the Eleventh Central Committee of the Communist Party of China (Dec. 22, 1978). 46 The Chinese Communist Party’s policy is usually carried out in party documents. For ex- ample, to promote rural reform in China, every year’s first party document states major rural reform policies from 1982 to 1986 and from 2004 to 2012. Thus, the “first party document” is the nickname of rural reform policy. These policies often introduce new reform measures that do not have sound legal grounds and will push law in new directions. The World Bank Legal Review172 China is in the long process of learning how to march to the rule of law. There are bound to be defects, problems, and loopholes in the legal system and in society as this process unfolds. For example, after drafting securities laws and regulations based on foreign models (introducing foreign law), listed companies with state assets are habitually interfered with by the state organs exercising power over them as state-owned enterprises. Based on these kinds of conditions, securities law and regulations operate differently than does the original model and their functions are very much restricted. Traits and Effects of Legal Transplantation in China At this point, China has a relatively comprehensive legal system. Although the legal system needs to be developed and perfected, its role in promoting economic and social development and constructing a new legal and social structure is widely recognized. The system has borrowed and transplanted many foreign laws and legal mechanisms that have been integrated into the system and play a significant role in providing readily gained experience and shortening the process of lawmaking. Why have these transplants been suc- cessfully integrated into the Chinese system? Integration of Transplanted and Aboriginal Concepts The modern Chinese legal system is built on Western legal patterns that have been transplanted on a grand scale. The traditional Chinese legal system (such as the Tang and Qing royal codes and legal apparatus) no longer exists in China. Nevertheless, the legal system has maintained certain traits, including strong nationalist and socialist characteristics. The traditional Chinese legal system, which lasted for more than 2,000 years, is an aboriginal legal system. The system was fundamentally trans- formed due to the formation of international markets and the effects of glo- balization. Although the legal culture and ideology of the system maintain a strong influence (both positive and negative), the Chinese structure and system have been entirely taken over. This transformation took place in the late Qing dynasty and early Nationalist Republic, when the royal “ancestor’s law and the traditional legal system” were abandoned and replaced by the Western legal system. Transplantation has since become a significant feature of the Chinese legal system.47 After the establishment of the People’s Republic of China in 1949, the new government of China abandoned the Western legal pattern and introduced the legal system of the Soviet Union. This massive process of transplantation ended in the early 1960s, when China broke away from the Soviet Union. During the disaster of the Cultural Revolution, the legal system modeled on the Soviet example was dismantled. With the ending of the Cultural Revolution, the Chinese government led by Deng Xiaoping 47 Zhou Shaoyuan, Chinese Legal Changes and Legal Transplantation in the 20th Century, 2 Chinese and Foreign Legal Science (1999). Legal Transplantation and Legal Development in Transitional China 173 decided to initiate structural reforms and open China’s door to the world. A policy of strengthening the legal system was begun to rebuild the ruined legal system. Since then, China has borrowed and introduced many foreign and international laws and mechanisms. Nevertheless, the dominant ideas in the process of transplantation are either “insisting on Chinese learning as the foundation and Western learning for practical use,” as introduced in the late Qing period, or “Chinese characteristics” (socialism under Chinese con- ditions), used currently, in which the transplanted laws and mechanisms are organically combined with traditional Chinese culture, popular ideology, and local environments. Therefore, China’s legal development is unlike that in Asia, Africa, and Latin America during the law-and-development movement of the 1960s, when foreign experts espoused the wholesale transplantation of the Western legal system. In the process of transplantation, China has emphasized the following concepts: • An insistence on the nationalistic and socialist nature of legal develop- ment, by which China tries to integrate transplanted laws and mecha- nisms into the framework of the legal regime embedded in Chinese cul- ture, particularly ideology and the dominant political doctrine. • An insistence on facing and solving real Chinese problems, by which China adopts a functional approach to set up clear targets for the trans- planted laws and mechanisms in order to combine the transplanted laws with Chinese social reality. • An insistence on national sovereignty and the principle of “taking facts as basis,”48 by which China’s legislative, administrative, and judicial agen- cies, after carefully analyzing the Chinese social environment and interna- tional needs, have maintained their authority of initiation and renovation and never blindly borrowed. • An insistence on integration within the national legal system, in which transplanting goes through careful study and adaptation in order to make individual transplants compatible with other laws and mechanisms. This type of transplantation might be described as “selective transplan- tation”—China has built its legal system with its own needs and purposes in mind. Although there are debates over the concepts of “Chinese charac- teristics” and socialism, and these concepts do need further explanation and substantiation, the concepts emphasized by China have the de facto effect of guaranteeing the independence of the Chinese legal system and maintaining its distinctive traits, and therefore integrating the introduced laws and me- chanics into the social environment and the existing Chinese legal framework. The unique approach taken by China to incorporating foreign elements into 48 Gu Ang’ran, Significance of Contract Law Legislation, in Legislative Materials on Contract Law of China, 37 (Law Publishing House 1999). See also Li Peichuan, Theory and Practice of Chinese Socialist Legislation 31–34 (China Legality Press 1991). The World Bank Legal Review174 its legal system represents a major innovation and has directly advanced the country’s economic development. As a result, China has been successful in avoiding an unhappy marriage of the transplanted and aboriginal systems as evidenced in other developing countries. This particular way of integration has also avoided the result of “rejection reaction”49 and guaranteed the natu- ralization of transplanted laws while maintaining their vitality. If legal trans- plants have played an important role in promoting social transition and reform in China, the above-mentioned general approaches, unique models, and tactics of legal transplantations were preconditions for success. Selective Transplantation “Selective adoption is the process of interplay by and mixing of the interna- tional rules and local cultural norms.”50 This concept, proposed by Potter, relates to the application of international rules and foreign laws in different countries, particularly in developing countries in today’s environment of glo- balization. China’s legal transplantation is by no means a blind or wholesale form of transplantation; to a great extent, it is a transplantation based on “self- need.” It requires that recipients scrutinize the target laws to be transplanted, the problems to be solved by transplanted laws, the possible social effects of transplantation, and the differences and similarities of the social environments of exporting and importing countries in order to come up with an active, pur- poseful, and selective legal transplant. In the current development wave, international institutions such as the World Bank and the International Monetary Fund often make the rule of law a prerequisite of financial support and ask recipient countries to implement overall or fundamental legal reform. Facing such requirements, many recipi- ent countries have no other recourse but to accept. There is nothing wrong with such requests, but they often overlook the internal environment of the recipient countries, making the countries passive in the process of reform and transplantation. Therefore, the transplanted laws often appear aimless or mis- matched to local needs or environments. In contrast, China, in its social transition and legal development, has adopted selective borrowing and transplantation rather than wholesale ab- sorption.51 In economic law, China adopted a series of foreign investment and trade laws and regulations when it opened the door to attract foreign 49 Wang Chenguang, Inter Borrowing and Absorption of Legal Systems of Different Countries—An Important Topic in Comparative Law, 4 China Legal Science (1992). 50 Pitman Potter, Selective Adoption and Institutional Capacity Building: Methods of Applying In- ternational Rules under the Impacts of Globalization, in The Hypothesis of “Selective Application” and China’s Legal Practice 2 (Pitman Potter & Gu Xiaorong ed., Shanghai Academy of Social Sciences Press 2009). 51 Pitman Potter, Selective Adaptation of Economic Governance Norms in China: Transparency and Autonomy in Local Context, in Pitman & Gu Xiaorong, id., at 30. Chen Yun, On the Approaches of China’s Rule of Law Resources, in Legal Transplantation and Legal Naturalization 298 (He Qinhua ed., Law Publishing House 2001). Legal Transplantation and Legal Development in Transitional China 175 investors and businesses. At the same time, China made a number of rules in the areas of foreign currency exchange, choices of laws, and management of joint ventures in order to maintain autonomy in conducting foreign trade. In the political field, China emphasizes its socialist nature and the Communist Party’s leading role and rejects the doctrine of separation of powers while it explores efficient means of restricting power, actively borrows and intro- duces foreign laws of legal supervision and control of governmental power, and sets up anticorruption bureaus in the procuratorial organs. In the process of judicial reform, China has pushed for adjudicative reform based on the ad- versarial model of common law while hesitating to adopt fully the principle of judicial independence; it introduced the reform of evidence rules based on the foreign evidence structure; and it actively promoted China’s guiding case system, based on the pattern of case law.52 These selective and adapted trans- plants play effective and practical roles with clear purposes in the incremental process of reform. Openness and Tolerance for Transplanted Laws Chinese reform has another characteristic: to allow a “bold charge” (da dan chuang),53 even new methods may be incompatible with the current rules. Generally speaking, Chinese reform adopts an incremental approach and fol- lows a piecemeal path, but it also encourages bold experiments and tolerates failures,54 including in the process of legal transplantation. In the aspects of structure and legal framework, particularly in the area of reforming concrete rules and institutes, the bold introduction and transplanta- tion of foreign effective laws and mechanisms have been a regular practice in pushing legal reform. Theoretically, there is a consensus that “borrowing and absorbing foreign laws cannot take the distinction of capitalism and socialism as a standard for borrowing and absorbing, but take the functional approach as standards to test whether the borrowing and absorbing is conducive to so- cial reform and economic development or not.”55 Transplants of concrete rules and mechanisms have affected many areas of the law. In the field of civil law, transplants have included the right to privacy, spiritual damages, and the principle of changing situations; in the criminal field, presumption of innocence, exclusion of illegal evidence, and evidence rules; in the administrative law field, administrative litigation, ad- ministrative permission, and protection of private information; and in the 52 Detailed reform is demonstrated in Supreme People’s Court, The Third Five-Year Reform Pro- gram of the People’s Courts (Mar. 2009). See also Xia Jinwen, Contemporary Chinese Judicial Re- form: Achievements, Problems and Future—An Analysis of People’s Courts, 1 China Legal Science (2010); Huang Zaizai, On Legal Transplantation and Establishment of China’s Case Law System, 4 Shanghai Carders Management College of Pol. & L. Rev. (2002). 53 The phrase “bold charge” was used by Deng Xiaoping when he made his famous visit to Shenzhen and encouraged further reforms in 1991. 54 Cao Ying & Hu Liguo ed., Xiaoping’s Centenary 551 –52 ( Jinghua Press 2004). 55 Wang, supra note 49. The World Bank Legal Review176 commercial and economic law field, company law, anti-unfair competition, protection of consumer rights, intellectual property rights, and the stock market. In the social protection field, a social security and social insurance system is garnering attention.56 The Chinese model of legal transplantation has had significant impacts on social transition and economic development. It facilitates the integration of the existing system with the transplanted system by reducing the conflicts be- tween them; at the same time, it exerts enormous momentum for social transi- tion. A good example is in the field of foreign investment: China has success- fully introduced many foreign laws and at the same time kept transplanted laws compatible with society. Thus, the transplanted laws and mechanisms maintain their vitality and effectiveness in the Chinese environment while promoting the transformation of the old legal and social systems. This model creates a vital framework that is capable of accommodating the contradictions of innovation and status quo and of reform and stability. The Chinese model promotes a mixed legal system. China’s current legal system is an open system that has absorbed positive experience from many foreign and international systems. It is based on a continental legal tradi- tion and actively borrows from the common law tradition, for example, in the fields of commercial law and banking law. This mode of transplantation implements the cost-effective formation of a modern legal system in line with international practice and development in other countries. Legal transplanta- tion has the advantage of providing legal rules more advanced than existing ones in developing countries. Rather than following the conventional method of going through all the developmental stages, legal transplantation may help a developing country effectively and efficiently upgrade its old-fashioned system. When China started to foster social reform and economic develop- ment, it could not wait for slow autogenous development but looked at more advanced systems with experience in the market economy; nor could it ac- cept the wholesale transplantation of foreign legal systems. By using this new innovative method of legal transplantation, China adopted market rules and mechanisms that have proved successful in other countries and successfully built a new market system and developed new market behavior patterns. The Chinese model pushes social reform and development. Chinese legal transplantation is never made without a clear purpose; therefore, legal trans- plantation is always directed toward tackling particular problems or issues. This problem-oriented approach is based on social reality and effectively 56 See Chen Xiaojun, On Contract Law Evolution in China, 6 Commercial L. Research (1999); Yu Guohua, On Comparative Study of China’s Contract Law, 2 Exploration (2000); Li Xiaoming, On the Presumption of Innocence Principle and Its Legislation, 6 China Prosecutor (2005); Wu Weishan, Calling for Legislative Efforts for Presumption of Innocence, 7 People’s Forum (2005); Wei Zong, Major Points of Administrative Litigation Law, 6 China Legal Science (1988); Ren Erxin, Economic Analysis of Commercial Legislation in China, 2 Gansu College of Pol. & L. Rev. (2001); Chen Yadong, Several Important Issues in Social Insurance Law Making, 6 Social Protec- tion Research (2009). Legal Transplantation and Legal Development in Transitional China 177 plants the transplanted rules in Chinese soil. The function and potential effect of facilitating social development are embedded at the beginning of any process of transplantation. Conclusion Although some scholars claim that “the amount of innovation in law is small and borrowing and imitation is of central importance in understanding the course of legal change,”57 China’s experience shows that legal transplantation as a means of legal reform and development requires innovation: innovation in the methods and ways of transplantation, and innovation in the content of transplanted laws and mechanisms to ensure that they fit into the recipient le- gal system. Legal transplantation is conducted not for the transplantation per se but for social development. The Chinese approach toward legal transplan- tation and the selective strategy of transplantation constitute an innovative model that enables the recipient legal system to be reformed and revitalized, which in return empowers society to accept successful experience from other countries and to rise to the challenges of social transition, modernization, and globalization. 57 Orucu, supra note 13. 179 Rule of Law as a Watermark China’s Legal and Judicial Challenges Stéphanie Balme Because the law and legal systems are crucial in promoting business interac- tions in the course of globalization, one might well ask, what is the status of the law and the legal system in China, the world’s second-biggest economy?1 This chapter answers that question by examining the major turning points in Chinese legal theory and legal practices since the 1990s, when China be- came a global economic and political actor. It covers some of the major ac- complishments of the People’s Republic of China (PRC) since the end of the Mao era and the beginning of Deng Xiaoping’s “open door policy” in 1978 and after China’s accession to the World Trade Organization (WTO) in 2001. Under Deng Xiaoping, law reforms legitimized the process of economic change. The legal framework affected business growth, while China’s wealth helped build a modern court system. Generally, access to justice for ordinary citizens is bet- ter today than ever before in Chinese history. After three decades, reform objectives have evolved from quantitative reforms to more qualitative reforms. This chapter explores some of the key constraints and challenges facing China today in terms of legal and judicial practices. The lack of guarantee to a fair trial is a recurring concern. One might well ask if Chinese law is inherently unfair because it denies due process or be- cause of deficient enforcement mechanisms. Reform of China’s legal and judi- cial systems relies on a balance among the country’s ruling party and various legal groups with diverging opinions and standards. Supremacy of the con- stitution, the law in action rather than in statutes, and legal certainty are fun- damental challenges in building a rule of law in China. Legal certainty refers to clarity, predictability, and fairness in the implementation of legal rules. New to China’s legal tradition, this Western standard has been translated into Chinese ( falü quedingxing) even though it does not yet have a legal recognition. The author wishes to thank Professor Wang Chenguang (Tsinghua University), Ms. Marina Lou, and M. Can Zhao (Sciences Po Paris) for their comments on an earlier version of this chapter. The author is entirely responsible for its final content. 1 World Bank, Doing Business (World Bank 2004). The World Bank Legal Review180 From Laws of Power to the Power of the Law? The difficulty in establishing a genuine and innovative rule of law in China can be explained by the fact that, at the conceptual level, traditional law has been repeatedly rejected by China’s own lawmakers. The modern law that exists is a combination of a system influenced by Western legality,2 the Maoist legacy (a combination of Stalinist theories with Chinese characteristics), and traditional legal reasoning as well as modern court practices. After the establishment of the PRC in October 1949 by Mao Zedong, a Soviet-style revolutionary regime of criminal justice was implemented. The new government regarded the existing system of law as a straitjacket that aided criminal suspects and in turn restricted its own prosecutorial powers. The anti- rightist movement in 1957, which witnessed the persecution of hundreds of thousands of people, further marginalized the role of law in society. In 1959, the Ministry of Justice was abolished. During the Cultural Revolution, from 1966 to 1976, the poorly shaped legal system, which lacked fundamental stat- utes such as criminal law, civil law, and administrative law, was almost entirely abolished. Only after the disastrous Cultural Revolution did reformist leader Deng Xiaoping use law to promote his policies: legal changes in China in 1978 were a technical response as well as a political answer to the fragmentation of the state under Mao. This is the point at which China began to take the role of law seriously and to embark on the current process of legal construction.3 In assessing China’s main achievements in terms of legal and judicial developments since 1978, this chapter focuses on two areas: the legislative arena and access to justice. Compared to the anarchical and rigorous charis- matic rule of the Maoist period, modern law has become, at least in theory, a legitimate instrument of public action both for authorities and for civil soci- ety. To use Max Weber ’s typology, China has moved from a charismatic type of authority to a more rational-legal authority where legitimacy derives from the existence of a legal order. However, as shown in this chapter, the rheto- ric of the rule of law is often confined to a formula of legal positivism, or pure theory. Important New Regulatory Policies The development of China’s current legal system dates to the late 1970s. The founding text is a speech given by Deng Xiaoping on December 13, 1978, an- nouncing the “policy of opening up,” as well as the official communiqué of December 22, 1978, published at the end of the third plenary session of the 11th Central Committee of the Chinese Communist Party (CCP). This com- muniqué formally abolished the dominant party policy of class struggle and 2 Philip C. Huang, Chinese Civil Justice: Past and Present (Rowman & Littlefield 2010). 3 See Wang Zhenmin & Li Zhenghui, The Rule of Law History, Theory and Criticism, 80(6) L. & Phil. Lib. 647–70 (2007). Rule of Law as a Watermark 181 the orthodox Marxist conception of law, according to which law is an instru- ment of bourgeois or proletarian dictatorship. The period between 1978 and 1982 marked a transition in terms of the Chinese legal system. The CCP clearly controlled the legal reform agenda. With the trial of the Gang of Four (November 1980 to January 1981), the new regime demonstrated its willingness to use legal instruments for dispute reso- lution (despite clear flaws in the trial, such as insufficient legal representa- tion, evidence errors, and political instruction to the special court). The work carried out since then has been considerable: restoration of the Ministry of Justice, rehabilitation of victims of the Cultural Revolution and the antiright- ist movement, and enactment of a new constitution, followed by a decade referred to by some Western academics as “legal bulimia.” The Struggle between Two Philosophies: Rule by Law and Rule of Law The idea of “rule by law” gradually emerged as the nation transformed from a planned economy to a state market economy. The fifth National People’s Con- gress (NPC) adopted the current constitution of the PRC on December 4, 1982. Comprising 138 articles, the constitution reflects a major change that shifts the primary task of the state from a class struggle to economic development and social reform. It stipulates the objectives of the state, the fundamental po- litical and economic systems of the country, a list of basic citizens’ rights, and the structure and power of the political regime. In June 1985, the first of a series of educational campaigns on the “popular- ization of the law” (pufa) was launched with the idea of creating a Chinese “so- ciety governed by law” ( fazhi shehui) and not “rule by men” (renzhi). The main slogan was a call to “reinforce the legal system and improve legislative qual- ity” ( jianquan de lifa zhidu yu hao de lifa zhiliang). In the 1990s, China adapted many international economic and trade laws with a view to the country’s ac- cession to the WTO. Over a period of more than 20 years, a genuine system of economic and trade laws was thus instituted. Until 2004, constitutional amendments were concerned almost exclusively with changing the orthodoxy of economic matters: namely, the diversification of property rights (1988), the establishment of a socialist market economy (1993), the acceptance or recogni- tion of the individual and semiprivate economy (1999), and the recognition of private property rights (2004).4 Moreover, based on previously existing contract laws, the 1999 economic contract law (symbolically promulgated on October 1, the date of the found- ing of the PRC) further validated the principles of autonomy, freedom, and equality of contracting parties. The law is voluminous (more than 400 arti- cles) and was rapidly disseminated in consideration of investors, particularly 4 See also Donald Clarke, Peter Murrell, & Susan Whiting, The Role of Law in China’s Economic De- velopment, available at http://econweb.umd.edu/~murrell/articles/ChinaInstitutions.pdf. http://econweb.umd.edu/~murrell/articles/ChinaInstitutions.pdf The World Bank Legal Review182 foreigners.5 Contract law is now involved in almost every commercial transac- tion in China. Article 26 gives contracting parties the right to request adjust- ment or even rescission of a valid contract but also sets up strict precedents. It aims to bring more certainty to an uncertain economic situation, stating: After a contract is legally formed, in view of objective circumstances not anticipated by the parties when the contract was formed, caused neither by force majeure nor commercial risks, and significant changes occur such that continuing the performance of the contract is unfair and inequitable to one party or the objective of the con- tract cannot be fulfilled, then a party or both parties may request the People’s Court to modify or rescind this contract. Ten years later, in the aftermath of the international economic crisis, the Supreme People’s Court (SPC) issued a judicial interpretation of the 1999 eco- nomic contract law to provide guidance on the right to rescind or modify a contract when a “fundamental change of circumstances” has occurred. A New Objective: “An Administration Based on Law” Between the mid-1980s and China’s entry into the WTO in December 2001, the government focused on enhancing the administrative law system to control governmental authority, which had previously been unlimited, and on adapt- ing the legal system to comply with international norms. This period saw the re-emergence of administrative law and use of the slogan “an administration based on law” ( yifa xingzheng). By the mid-1990s, theories on administrative law were said to be “exploding,”6 with the appointment of more administra- tive law professors and the founding of the National School of Administration (now called the Chinese Academy of Governance). In April 1989, a new administrative litigation law allowed citizens and all legal persons to bring legal challenges against “specific administrative actions.” Through the mid-2000s, various regulations were passed to allow administrative sanctions, such as the Regulations on Public Security Manage- ment and Sanctions (Zhi’an guanli chufa tiaoli), and to restrict the power of administrative organs. Passed in the mid-1990s, the State Compensation Law (Article 2) states: Where State organs or State functionaries, in violation of the law, abuse their functions and powers infringing upon the lawful rights and interests of the citizens, legal persons and other organizations, thereby causing damage to them, the victims shall have the right to State compensation in accordance with this Law.7 5 Available at http://www.law-lib.com/law/. 6 See Zhang Li, Le contrôle juridictionnel de la légalité des actes administratifs en Chine: Eléments d’analyse comparée des contentieux administratifs chinois et français (Bruylant 2010). 7 http://en.chinacourt.org/public/detail.php?id=109. http://en.chinacourt.org/public/detail.php?id=109 http://www.law-lib.com/law/ Rule of Law as a Watermark 183 Other notable laws were the Law on Administrative Punishments (1996), the Law on Administrative Supervision (1997), the Implementation Regula- tions (2004), and the Administrative Licensing Law (2004).8 In ancient China, people beat a drum outside the government offices ( ya- men) to start litigation, to petition a visiting imperial envoy, or “to appeal to the emperor” ( gao yu zhuang). As recently as a few decades ago, the petition system had not been standardized. Under Mao, the government developed a comprehensive network of agencies, the xinfang (letters and visits) offices, throughout the county, as well as a petition system (shangfang). These mecha- nisms were “to petition the government for a redress of grievances by means of letters (xin) or visits ( fang),” according to Isabelle Thireau and Hua Linshan.9 The xinfang system today looks different. Under Mao, only people defined as “legitimate” could express grievances. Nowadays, the xinfang offices must, in principle, allow anyone to exercise his or her constitutional rights. Also, under Mao, the petition system mostly involved the denunciation of enemies and counterrevolutionaries. Now, it aims to maintain social stability by com- pensating people and solving people’s problems. In May 2005, a principle of “solving problems at the grassroots level” (ba xinfang wenti jiejue zai jiceng) was adopted. For the first time, an individual or organization could not retaliate against petitioners; if it did, it would face legal action. Although there has been an increase in the number of petitioners (12.72 million letters, calls, or visits in 2003, for example) and a growing number of visits, the success rate (in terms of petitioners’ cases being accepted) for these visits has always been low, less than 1 percent, according to unofficial statements. In the wake of Li Maorun v. Langzhong Police Station in 2001, citizens can sue local governments for actions in violation of their rights, including ad- ministrative punishments, administrative coercive measures, interference with the operation of enterprises, refusal to take action or perform an obli- gation, unlawful demands for performance of duties, and violations of indi- vidual rights or property rights. Cases commonly involve encroachment by the government on the interests and rights of ordinary citizens, inadequate compensation for land appropriation, illegal land seizures, and expropriation or house demolition. Since the mid-2000s, administrative litigation and land- mark cases involving the government have increased as citizens become more comfortable using legal measures to protect their property from government violation. The relationship between the xinfang system and the judicial system re- mains unclear. In 2011, it is still difficult for the judiciary to give transparent and consistent judgments or efficient enforcement. Judicial review of government action is not permitted in situations of “national defense,” a loosely interpret- ed concept, or foreign affairs. In addition, judicial review is not permitted for 8 See Chen Jianfu, Chinese Law: Context and Transformation 207–60 (Martinus Nijhoff, Brill Academic 2008). 9 Isabelle Thireau & Hua Linshan, Les ruses de la démocratie: Protester en Chine (Le Seuil 2010). The World Bank Legal Review184 “abstract administrative action,” which refers to rule and policy-making activ- ities. The relationship between the state and citizens in public administration is still problematic in terms of not being regulated by due process. A Growing Recognition of Labor and Economic Rights By the late 1990s, restructuring of state-owned enterprises (SOEs) had led to the closure, merger, or privatization of underperforming SOEs and the laying off of more than 30 million workers (xiagang zhigong). Although various ar- rangements were made for the laid-off workers (for example, buying out em- ployment, reducing salaries, and providing assistance for self-employment), the smashing of the “iron rice bowl” (i.e., job security and guaranteed ben- efits) triggered massive labor disputes and unrest. Scholars and think tanks developed a five-year program (1996–2001) for the government with the objective of developing labor protection laws in the new market situation. The Labor Law of 1999 (Laodong Fa) states that it will “protect the legitimate rights and interests of laborers, re-adjust labor rela- tionship, establish and safeguard the labor system compatible to the socialist market economy, and promote economic development and social progress” (Article 1). It further states that laborers have the right to equal treatment, choose occupations, ob- tain remunerations, take rests, have holidays and leaves, receive labor safety and sanitation protection, get training in professional skills, enjoy social insurance and welfare treatment, and submit ap- plications for settlement of labor disputes, and other labor rights stipulated by law. (Article 3) China’s Labor Law of January 1, 2008, requires that labor contracts be in writing and limits the use of term contracts and probationary periods for em- ployees. Their length of probationary periods is limited based on the terms of the employment contract, with a maximum of six months. “Virtually every violation of the law gives the employee the right to sue the employer for pen- alties and damages in the local employment arbitration bureau or in the local courts,” explains lawyer Steve Dickinson.10 In March 2001, China ratified the International Covenant on Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights, but it still places a reservation on obligations re- garding Article 8, which guarantees trade union rights and the right to free- dom of association. Legislative activity in this area developed rapidly as the workers’ movement intensified in 2007 and 2008. Four important laws were adopted to face this new legal challenge: the Law on Prevention and Treat- ment of Occupational Diseases, the Employment Promotion Law, the Law on Labor Dispute Mediation and Arbitration, and the Social Insurance Law. 10 Steve Dickinson, China’s New Labor Law: Power to the People, China International Business Magazine (2007), available at http://www.chinalawblog.com. http://www.chinalawblog.com Rule of Law as a Watermark 185 Legal Empowerment at the Local Level According to Zhu Jingwen’s quantitative measure of rule of law reforms in China, in 1979, there were 15 laws, 68 administrative regulations, and 72 local regulations. In 2006, there were 36 laws, 164 national administrative regula- tions, and 14,124 local regulations.11 Thus, between 1979 and 2006, the average annual growth of national laws and national administrative regulations was around 11 percent, compared with more than 30 percent for local regulations. These figures reveal that there was a massive legislative effort over 30 years, particularly at the local level. This situation contributed to a growing deficit of legal visibility and accessibility of regulations and laws in China. With China’s integration into the international economy through the WTO and the increasing development of the Internet, the decade of 2000–2010 was characterized by new and multiple interactions between authorities and civil society in defining the legal reform agenda. The Law on Legislation (Lifa Fa), enacted in March 2000, was designed to rationalize the system and regu- late legislative processes. It also set up procedures for public participation, such as publication of legislative drafts and public hearings (tingzheng). In March 2008, the chairman of the Standing Committee of the National People’s Congress, Wu Bangguo, controversially announced that a socialist le- gal system with Chinese characteristics had been fundamentally accomplished. “There are laws to cover basically every area of economic, political, cultural and social activities in the country,” he stated in a report on China’s Assembly.12 Table 1. Number of Laws and Regulations in China, 1979-2005 Year Law Administrative Regulation Local Regulation Amount 1979 15 68 72 404 1982 21 145 485 1055 1989 15 111 1,508 3,339 1991 27 111 1,601 3,879 1996 40 118 3,475 6,349 2000 31 171 5,628 8,846 2005 36 164 14,124 18,121 Average Annual Rate of Growth 11.8% 10.7% 33.1% 21.3% Source: Zhu Jingwen, Report on China Law Development: Database and Indicators (RUC Press 2007). Translation S. Balme. 11 Zhu Jingwen, Report on China Law Development: Database and Indicators (RUC Press 2007). 12 Id. The World Bank Legal Review186 Toward Better Access to Justice China’s judicial system resumed in 1979, after the chaotic events of the Cultural Revolution. The reform of the judiciary must be assessed through the lens of judicial transformation under the Maoist regime. During successive Maoist campaigns, particularly in 1950–53, 1957–58, 1967–71, and 1975–76, the num- ber of cases registered as criminal cases exceeded the number of civil cases. Post-Mao China’s legal and judicial reforms were characterized by stop-and- go cycles. For example, the last historical period, after Mao’s death, when the number of criminal cases almost reached the number of civil cases was during the 1983 “strike hard” ( yanda) campaign against criminal suspects. In 1981, Deng Xiaoping used the trial of the Gang of Four to display the regime’s intentions to govern with reference to the law instead of by indi- vidual political decisions. Since then, ordinary, daily justice has been largely depoliticized and professionalized. According to Professor Zhu Jingwen, the percentage of judgments made through formal procedures increased from 16.5 percent to 35.7 percent between the mid-1990s and the mid-2000s.13 Ac- cording to the China National Bureau of Statistics, recent growth in the num- ber of civil disputes has been irregular: from 5,346,986 in 2008 to 6,458,573 in 2009 and 4,980,721 in 2010. Altogether, between 2008 and 2010, Chinese juris- dictions received and adjudicated 16,786,280 cases. The number of marriage and heritage disputes (1,286,437 cases in 2008; 1,423,180 cases in 2010) and the number of contract disputes (2,905,603 cases in 2008; 3,222,555 cases in 2010) also increased during this period.14 In 30 years, successive reform plans have evolved from quantitative re- forms (reestablishing a judiciary, building courts, hiring judges, and training lawyers) to more qualitative reforms such as enhancing the quality of judi- cial training, improving access to justice, and creating alternative dispute- resolution techniques. For litigants who have access to the Internet, judi- cial services are increasingly available in China, and, according to author Bi Shaofeng, legal aid services are more developed than in the past in coastal areas and in remote places.15 However, few legal aid offices or legal clinics (falü yuanzhusuo, falü zhensuo) exist in rural areas or for nonprivileged categories of the population such as the migrant workers or disabled persons. An Emerging Country with an Emerging Judiciary China is a centralized state with a decentralized judicial administration that is largely funded and supervised by local governments. All civil servants in the judicial organs are appointed by local people’s congresses. The SPC, not the Ministry of Justice, supervises the judiciary at various levels through a hierar- 13 Zhu Jingwen, Judicial Transformation and Legal Sociology in China (2008). 14 http://www.stats.gov.cn. 15 Bi Shaofeng, Rural Legal Clinics: An Educational Handbook (China Law Press 2010). http://www.stats.gov.cn Rule of Law as a Watermark 187 chical system of more than 3,000 courts. Politics and law committees (Zhengfa wei) of the CCP at various levels are in charge of the direction and cooperation of courts, procuratorates, and police. The committees ensure the CCP’s leader- ship over judicial issues in every tribunal. The public security organs ( gong’an jiguan) represent the principal police authority, which is responsible for con- ducting criminal investigations and, with the authorization of procuratorates (except under certain circumstances), arresting suspects. The committee also ensures the CCP’s leadership over judicial issues in every tribunal. Lawyers are kept under control by both the legislative and the judicial branches. Since 2002, anyone with a university degree can take the Unified Judicial Exam (Tongyi sifa kaoshi), which is common to all legal professions, including lawyers, judges, and prosecutors. Every year, approximately 300,000 candi- dates (50 percent of whom are from 11 provinces, although the largest por- tion are from Beijing and Guangdong) take this competitive exam. Since 2010, the passing rate has been slightly above 20 percent. Among the 90 percent of undergraduates who take the exam, only a minority are law students who specialize in law. However, overall, the number of graduates from law schools or legal institutes in China increased from around 8,000 in 1996 to more than 135,000 in 2010. There are more than 640 “real” law schools around the coun- try, and the legal education market is booming. In 2002, among the 360,000 candidates who registered to take the exam in order to obtain a Certificate of Legal Practice, the success rate was 8 percent, in- cluding a very small proportion of candidates from the remote western regions. In 1980, the Provisional Law on Lawyering in the PRC defined lawyers as “state legal workers” and law offices as “legal counseling services” ( falü gu- wenchu). In 1986, the Chinese National Lawyer’s Association was established in Beijing, with branches throughout the country. By 2012, a lawyer was de- fined as “a professional who legally obtains a lawyer’s certificate and pro- vides the society with legal services.” The Lawyers Law (Lüshi fa), as amended in October 2007, recognized the specificity of the lawyers as a legal profession. However, judges and prosecutors still greatly outnumber lawyers. Except in the biggest cities and along the coastal provinces, the total num- ber of lawyers per habitant in China is very low. In addition, the distribution of lawyers in China is uneven. In 1996, 100,198 people were “employed as attorneys” (this number refers to all categories of personnel working in a law firm; lüshi gongzuo renyuan); in 2011, this number was 204,000.16 This category can be divided between full-time attorneys (47,879; zhuanzhi lüshi), part-time attorneys (20,243; jianzhi lüshi), and legal workers ( falü gongzuozhe). From 1998 to 2006, the number of people employed as “lawyers” increased from 101,220 to 164,516. The number of full-time attorneys increased dramatically (from 51,008 to 122,242), while the number of so-called nonprofessional lawyers (not employed on a full-time basis) decreased from 17,958 to 8,068. In 2002, after 16 http://www.stats.gov.cn. http://www.stats.gov.cn The World Bank Legal Review188 introduction of the Unified Judicial Exam for the professions of lawyers, judges, and procuratorates, the number of nonprofessional lawyers (or legal workers) decreased considerably. A majority of lawyers are now on full-time status and are supposedly fully qualified. According to Sida Liu and Ethan Michelson’s studies on the development of the legal profession in China, the economic and institutional “vulnerabili- ties” of Chinese lawyers constitute a difficult issue. Lawyers in medium-size cities often have to rely on state judicial agencies to find business and guaran- tee the annual renewal of their license. Lawyers have to contend with “dead- beat clients who fail to pay their legal fees, exploitative employers who fail to support their professional work and to protect their social security,” and insti- tutional actors “who interfere with and obstruct [the lawyers’] work.”17 This situation weakens the role of lawyers in courts and constrains their capacity to represent clients. China’s Judges Law (Faguan fa) was adopted in 1997 and amended in 2001 after the establishment of the Unified Judicial Exam. Theoretically and legally, all judges in China have passed the exam. Their status is somewhat ambiguous: they are called “judge” ( faguan) in everyday life and “adjudica- tor” (shenpanyuan) in court. Article 2 of the Judges Law states that “judges are the judicial personnel who exercise the judicial authority of the State.” They shall “faithfully implement the constitution and laws, and serve the people whole-heartedly” (Article 3). The functions and duties of judges in China are different from those of their counterparts in the West; Chinese judges must “take part in a trial as a member of a collegial panel or try a case alone accord- ing to law” as well as perform all other functions and duties as provided by law (Article 5). In addition, they must accept legal supervision and “supervi- sion by the masses” (Article 7). In 1999, the SPC published its first guiding instrument for enhancing the judiciary: the Five-Year Reform Program for People’s Courts. This document aimed to enhance the efficiency and fairness of adjudication by reforming the courts’ “inquisitorial” trial pattern to a more “adversarial” trial pattern. Since then, the main slogan of the SPC has been “judicial efficiency and judicial fairness” (sifa xiaolü yu sifa gongzheng). In 2004, Measures on the Management of the Publication of Judgment Documents and Several Opinions of the Supreme People’s Court on Strengthening the Work on Judicial Openness in People’s Courts were published, completing the transition. A second Five-Year Reform Program for People’s Courts (2004–08) stressed the importance of bringing greater professionalism and integrity to the judi- ciary. The reform program called for courts to begin “exploring within a certain geographic area the implementation of a system of uniform recruitment and 17 See Ethan Michelson & Sida Liu, What Do Chinese Lawyers Want? Political Values and Legal Practice (Brookings Institution 2010), available at http://www.indiana.edu/~emsoc/Publi- cations/Chapter14_Michelson_Liu.pdf. See also local reports such as those found at http:// www.fabang.com/a/20111207/460510.html. http://www.indiana.edu/~emsoc/Publi�cations/Chapter14_Michelson_Liu.pdf http://www.indiana.edu/~emsoc/Publi�cations/Chapter14_Michelson_Liu.pdf http://www.fabang.com/a/20111207/460510.html http://www.fabang.com/a/20111207/460510.html Rule of Law as a Watermark 189 uniform assignment of judges for duties in the basic-level courts.” The SPC also explored the establishment of guaranteed national funding for local courts by inserting provisions in central and provincial government budgets. Conflict of governance (budget, nomination, management, and judicial inde- pendence) between central and local judicial authorities remains a subject of concern for some judicial authorities. A network of modern courts, inspired by Western architectural styles (Greek temple or US Supreme Court–style), affects citizens’ and litigants’ per- ception of the judiciary. To that end, the SPC developed a policy of erecting new court buildings and investing in hardware and access to justice. Many older court buildings have been demolished. In 2007, the litigation fees’ man- agement system was reformed, separating the collection of litigation fees from courts’ expenditures. Litigation fees are no longer directly handed to courts but are paid instead by litigants through designated banks that are often directly located within the courts. In April 2007, a regulation from the State Council (the Chinese government) unified charging standards and promoted lower litigation fees for civil and administrative disputes. This regulation to reduce litigation fees “to diminish ordinary people’s burden and facilitate access to justice” had a direct and immediate impact on the Chinese courts’ source of income.18 In September 2007, an article in the Legal Daily explained that courts lost an average of 53.55 percent of their rev- enues due to this change. Consequently, 2.4 billion renminbi was allocated to compensate local tribunals for the losses in budgets. In 2008 and 2009, the situation improved. Most courts have received partial or total compensation for losses and have implemented the regulation forbidding arbitrary fees. In March 2009, the SPC promulgated a third Five-Year Program for the Reform of People’s Courts (2009–13), initiating a new round of court modern- ization. This program was formulated with a view to maintaining social fair- ness and justice and satisfying the new demands and new expectations of the general public regarding the judiciary. Much attention was paid to aspects of “judicial efficiency” such as the cost and speed of judicial procedures as well as the enforcement of judicial decisions. These qualities are crucial in the effort to build trust and confidence among litigants. Since the mid-2000s, mediation has been given great significance by the Chinese Communist Party and therefore by all judicial organs. In 2009, the SPC, in its annual Report on the Work of People’s Courts, put forward the policy of mediation first, followed by a combination of mediation and adjudica- tion. The same year, the SPC promulgated the Opinion on the Establishment 18 See also the Report on the Implementation of the Central and Local Budgets for 2006 and on the Draft Central and Local Budgets for 2007, 9 (Ministry of Finance 2007), which states that in 2006, the central authorities supported the strengthening of government authority at the county and township levels. Funds were set aside in the central budget in 2006 to help lower-level procuratorial, judicial, and public security departments to improve conditions for process- ing cases. Available at http://www.chinaview.cn. http://www.chinaview.cn The World Bank Legal Review190 and Improvement of Dispute-Settlement Mechanisms with Coordination between Litigious and Non-Litigious Means. This opinion was a major step in the pro- motion of the development of multiple dispute-settlement mechanisms, including arbitration and administrative and civil mediation, to avoid the danger of forced, or imposed mediation. In June 2012, the SPC revealed a detailed Working Guide to Improve Judicial Efficiency (Tigaosifa xiaolu gongzuo zhinan). The guide’s emphasis is on the quality and the effectiveness of justice to enhance judicial efficiency, which refers to a sense of providing accessible, professional, and fair dispute-settlement services. This implies incentive mechanisms for judges, the simplification of complicated dispute settlement procedures, the professionalization of the judicial manage- ment system, and the reinforcement of a variety of dispute resolution mecha- nisms, including some alternative or nonlitigation procedures. The guide is the product of an innovative international collaboration with the European Union, the UN Development Programme (UNDP), and the Supreme People’s Court. It will provide a benchmark for local courts to use to evaluate their efficiency.19 China has stated its intention to undertake certain reforms, such as promot- ing open, publicly accessible courtroom proceedings, more media interaction and public outreach, and more public access to written judgments including judges’ rationale. Thus far, these reforms have been uneven and limited in terms of both their substance and their geographic scope. Although several reforms have been designed to strengthen the professionalism of the judiciary and to ad- dress judicial corruption and build public confidence, such as the passage of an ethics code for judges, they still need to be institutionalized and fairly, uni- formly, and effectively enforced. The improvement of the “hardware” of the legal and judicial systems has largely benefited plaintiffs and citizens in China. Civil justice in China has been overhauled. A broad range of reforms have been adopted, covering in- stitutional as well as procedural aspects. Although the general context is dif- ferent, the global aim of the reforms has been much the same as elsewhere in Europe where civil justice is being reformed: to ensure fair justice with greater efficiency in terms of both time and costs, in response to an increasing demand from the public at large. The Status of Human Rights vs Human Rights in Action In the late 1980s, the term fazhi (legal system) was gradually abandoned in favor of its homonym fazhi (rule of law), which implies the necessity of the establishment of a formal system to guarantee people’s rights and to check governmental power. In December 1999, a notion similar to the concept of 19 See Stéphanie Balme, Review of Efforts to Improve Judicial Efficiency and Costs (Governance for Equitable Development Aug. 2012). Rule of Law as a Watermark 191 rule of law but not yet due process was incorporated into China’s constitution. Article 5 states: No law or administrative or local rule and regulation shall con- travene the constitution. All state organs, the armed forces, all political parties and public organizations and all enterprises and undertakings must abide by the constitution and the law. All acts in violation of the constitution and the law must be investigated. No organization or individual may enjoy the privilege of being above the constitution and the law. Another major step toward reforming the post-Mao state is the progres- sive integration of human rights into Chinese law. Until the 1980s, human rights discourses were ignored or attacked. Today, Marxist critics of human rights still exist among some CCP leaders who con- tinue to advocate historical materialism, deny the notion of jus naturalism, em- phasize collective rights over individual rights, advocate equality rather than liberty, and prefer “real rights” (the right of subsistence, for example) over so-called formal rights, such as freedom of expression. However, Beijing has signed—if not ratified—most of the existing inter- national treaties or conventions related to human rights, including the Inter- national Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Racial Discrimination (March 1966), the Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimina- tion against Women (December 1979), the International Convention against Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punishment (of December 1984; although China does not yet recognize the competence of the committee against torture); the Convention on the Rights of the Child (No- vember 1989), the International Covenant on Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights (ICESC; 1997) and the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR; 1998). In 1991, the Chinese government published its first white paper on human rights. In 2009, a national action plan on human rights was officially launched, demonstrating a general yet genuine recognition of the morality of human rights as described by Michael Perry: “each and every born human being has inherent dignity which is inviolable.”20 The 1996 Criminal Procedure Law (CPL) recognizes the “principle of pre- sumption of innocence” (wuzui tuiding) of innocence without adopting the actual words, which are similar to those found in Article 11 of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights.21 Article 162(3) of the 1996 CPL states that, “if 20 Michael J. Perry, Toward a Theory of Human Rights (Cambridge U. Press 2006). 21 According to the law, everyone charged with a penal offense has the right to be presumed innocent until proved guilty in a public trial at which he or she has had all the guarantees necessary for his or her defense. Stéphanie Balme, La justice pénale en Chine: Son évolution et son avenir; Analyse du projet 2011 de réformes de la Loi de procédure pénale (Institut des Hautes Etudes sur la Justice 2012); available at http://www.ihej.org/la-justice-penale-en-chine-son -evolution-et-son-avenir/. http://www.ihej.org/la-justice-penale-en-chine-son-evolution-et-son-avenir/ http://www.ihej.org/la-justice-penale-en-chine-son-evolution-et-son-avenir/ The World Bank Legal Review192 the evidence is insufficient and thus the defendant cannot be found guilty, he/she shall be pronounced innocent accordingly on account of the fact that the evidence is insufficient and the accusation unfounded.” The right to life and the protection against cruel, inhuman, and degrading punishments (International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, Article 6, paragraph 1) restricts the use of the death penalty to the most serious crimes. China’s Criminal Law, Article 40, stipulates: “the death penalty should only be applied to criminals who have committed extremely serious crimes and be restricted and excluded for juveniles, pregnant women, mothers and the insane.” A penalty of death must be based on clear and convincing evidence, leaving no room for other explanations of the facts. The maximum term for concurrently applied sentences was raised from 20 to 25 years (Article 69), and individuals originally sentenced to life imprison- ment will be obliged to serve longer prison terms before they can be released through sentence reduction (Article 81). The most serious offenders will not be offered sentence reduction. However, the law requires lenient treatment of offenders aged 75 and older, and judges have been given more specific in- structions about how “lenient punishment” should be applied in sentencing (Articles 17 and 49). Additionally, in 2010, 13 crimes (among a total of 68) were removed from death penalty eligibility under criminal law. The official contestation, in the 1990s—following the Tiananmen Square incident—of the principle of the universality of human rights came not so much from a supposed Confucian tradition, but rather from a Marxist cri- tique. Human rights still are sometimes considered a threat to the political status quo. Finally, this contestation is paradoxically growing at a time when a new generation of human rights (e.g., animal rights and rights to reputation) are emerging in China. Both a developing country and an emerging power, Chinese authorities question the path of contemporary developed societies on human rights and the rule of law. However, it seems that China’s authorities also do not want their performance to be subjected to international scrutiny. The diversity of voices in China makes the judicial and legal systems more difficult to change now than immediately after the Cultural Revolution. Open debates, the vitality of public opinion, reflections on publicized trials, and ju- dicial cases are also assets as China’s rule of law faces new challenges. Rule of Law in China: Current Challenges and Future Perspectives Although the framework of law that has evolved since the end of the Cultural Revolution provides a foundation for rule of law, a more determined and sus- tained effort is necessary to reform China’s legal regime in depth. Experts observed a significant regression of the rule of law in the 2000s, under the guise of preserving social harmony. Wang Shengjun, the president Rule of Law as a Watermark 193 of the SPC, publicly advocated the policy of the “three supremes”: first, the supremacy of the party, then of the people, and finally of the constitution and the law. The many legal and judicial challenges faced by China can be sum- marized by the increasingly urgent need to create a systematic legal frame- work and a hierarchy of norms respectful of both collective and individual rights. Areas of potential reform include legal sources, legal writing and rea- soning, due process, the stability of legal institutions, the predictability of the judicial process, and legal certainty. Chinese judges are civil servants with no real power. The Ministry of Pub- lic Security, the principal police authority, holds the power to conduct inves- tigations and arrest suspects in criminal cases; a Politics and Law Committee (Zhengfa wei) is in charge of the direction and cooperation of people’s courts, people’s procuratorates, and the police. The committee also ensures the CCP’s leadership over judicial issues in every tribunal. Lawyers are kept under strict control by both the legislative and the executive branches. Conflicts of Norms After more than three decades of reforms, China’s legal developments are not immune from defects; some are serious, such as a lack of hierarchy of norms and inconsistency among rules, the absence of a transparent and comprehen- sive constitutional review system (weixian shencha), and a lack of harmoni- zation of law and judgments. Also, the CCP charter and regulations are de facto full-fledged laws. What, then, is China’s grundnorm? To show the complexity of the situation in China, this section focuses on the evolution of three domains of law: criminal procedure, property, and an- tidiscrimination. In criminal procedure and property law, abuses and legal uncertainty are mainly a consequence of unlawful behaviors, which are fa- cilitated by the vagueness and ambiguities of the law. In antidiscrimination regulations, legal discrimination leads to behavioral abuses against the basic principles of rule of law. The Criminal Procedure Law (CPL; 1996) and its amendments (2012) typ- ify how the inconsistencies among laws at different levels generate an opposi- tion to judicial discretion and foster a sense of arbitrariness. Ambiguities of and inconsistences among legal norms affect their credibility and reveal that the court system, which is not even charged with interpreting the law, is not a powerful institution. Chinese courts play very few roles in supervising the police during criminal investigations. Another example: the system of reha- bilitation through labor (RTL) (laojiao) is an administrative sanction taken by the police and the RTL committee without interference from the procuratorate or the tribunal. Under the RTL system, a person can be deprived of liberty without having interacted with any judicial authority. Although the CPL was revised in 2012, many ambiguities remain both with and within the Lawyers Law. Amended in October 2007, the Lawyers Law The World Bank Legal Review194 allows lawyers to meet with clients without the presence of police officers. Lawyers have an obligation of confidentiality but are limited by the fact that theycannot keep certain information secret (Article 38 of the Lawyers Law). In addition, a lawyer can be condemned if he or she influences a client not to con- fess to a crime (Article 38 of the CPL). In China, the absence of a guarantee to the right to a fair trial is a serious issue, especially because the right to remain silent is not clearly established. The CPL stipulates that evidence obtained through torture cannot be used as grounds for a verdict. However, the law emphasizes that accused persons must give “truthful answers” (rushi huida) and that “resistance to answer will be treated severely” (kangju congya). The March 2012 revision of the CPL ex- hibits a punitive philosophy, mainly based on the traditional Marxist notion of crime, and the goal of maintaining public order. (There are more than 60 references to the terms “raison d’Etat” or “state secrets” in the revision.) A lack of empowerment by the judges within the judicial system, in contradistinction to the role played by the public security forces, emphasizes the effectiveness of exceptional police procedures on ordinary judicial procedures. Legal guarantee of ownership rights is a fundamental characteristic of a state that has rule of law. China’s legal system does not provide legal certainty in this regard for the following reasons: the system of ownership is extremely complex in China and public ownership often trumps private ownership; the lack of legal quality (precise rules) leads to legal uncertainty; and the judicial system does not have a strong authority to regulate chaotic legal norms. In 1949, civil codes enacted under the previous, Nationalist, regime were abolished. Land reform policies in 1950 resulted in massive and violent land expropriations and the abolishment of the notion of private property and own- ership rights. The land collectivization that took place during the Maoist pe- riod led to the replacement of the notion of property rights (suoyou quan) with “a system of property” (suoyou zhi). After the Cultural Revolution, the aboli- tion of the people’s communes allowed a growing recognition of the notion of “real rights,” espoused by administrative regulations specifying rules of transfer and the attribution of rights. In 1986, the General Principles of Civil Law (Minfa tongze) defined, for the first time since the Kuomintang’s codes, the notion of property rights. The Rural Land Contracting Law of 2002 (Nongcun tudi chengbao Fa) clari- fied the rights and obligations of the rural household and the agricultural col- lective based on a contractual system (chengbao zhi). In 2007, after a decade of consultations and debates, a Property Law was adopted by 96.9 percent of the 2,889 legislators of the NPC, with 53 delegates opposing and 37 abstaining. In 2004, a constitutional amendment specified that “the lawful private property of citizens is inviolable” (Article 13). Yet, according to the Property Law of 2007, “the state may in the public interest [ gonggong liyi] expropriate or take over land for its use in accordance with the law and provide compat- ible compensation [xiangying buchang]” (Article 10, paragraph 3). Because the Rule of Law as a Watermark 195 notion of public interest is vague and the judiciary has almost no independent authority, the law does not provide protection or legal certainty to the people whose land is being expropriated. The legal system has improved in recent years in that access to property rights is now guaranteed. Still, because urban lands belong to the state and rural lands belong to collective organizations, owners’ rights are limited when expropriations are deemed justified by public authorities. For rural lands, each farmer must be allocated a land parcel based on a contractual system of 30 to 70 years, depending on the status of the land (cultivated land, forest land, etc.). As for nonrural lands, rights are delegated by the state, which can trans- fer, use, and exchange the land (the notion of sûreté in European systems). To fight against the many abusive expropriations that took place in China between 1990 and 2010, new local and administrative regulations have been passed, creating a chaotic legal structure. This lack of legal quality has led to increasing legal uncertainty. For example, a Law on Planification of urban and rural zones (Articles 22–26) was enacted in 2007, as was a resolution amend- ing the Land Management Law (Tudi guanli Fa). These texts present two major amendments to the existing system: “According to the needs of public inter- est, the state can expropriate [zhengshou] or requisition [zhengyong] land and provide adequate compensation.” In other words, the state can expropriate collectively owned land for the purposes of national projects such as dams, railroads, and highways through a transfer of land from collective owner- ship to state ownership, and requisition does not entail a change in owner- ship. The state can also temporarily lease land from a collective for public benefit, but in theory, it must return the land once the lease is over. These provisions include the rights to use and profit from contracted land, to profit from the transmission of the land’s management authority, and to organize and manage one’s own production. Judges review disputes on compensation for expropriated land based on the 2007 Administrative Law on Urban Land and Real Estate Property. According to Article 45 of that law, only the central government (some- times in coordination with provincial governments) can expropriate lands with the precondition of obtaining a “demolishing license.”22 Lands can be expropriated only for public service construction, not for commercial use, and transformation of farmlands into “industrial land” is limited. However, the distinction is primarily administrative, and courts seldom take expropria- tion cases. In most cases, local governments decide expropriations. Persistence of Legal Discrimination When he was working as a consultant to the World Bank on China’s labor legislation in the late 1990s, Ronald Brown noticed a job advertisement that 22 Li Bin, Droit de la Propriété et Expropriation en Droit Chinois (Université Paris I 2010). The World Bank Legal Review196 read, “Seeking an office clerk. Female, decent height and appearance. ‘All five facial organs must be in the right place’ [wu guan duanzheng].”23 In China, discrimination based on physical appearance is common.24 Although general antidiscrimination provisions are included in various laws, administrative regulations and local regulations remain discriminatory.25 The 1982 constitution recognizes that “all citizens are equal before the law” (Article 33). Women enjoy equal rights with men in all spheres of life— political, economic, cultural, and social—including family life (guaranteed by Article 48 of the constitution and the 2005 Law on the Protection of the Rights and Interests of Women). The Labor Law of 1995 states that employees must not be discriminated against on the basis of nationality, gender, or religious belief (Article 12). The 1991 Disabled Persons Protection Law, amended in 2008, protects “the lawful rights and interests of people with disabilities.” Professor Li Dun, a scholar at the Chinese Academy of Social Sciences, showed that the Civil Servants Recruitment Health Check-Up Standard (Gongwuyuan pinyong tijian biaozhun) issued by the Ministry of Health and the Ministry of Human Resources and Social Security was unconstitutional.26 This “standard” prevents people with various physical conditions, includ- ing HIV/AIDS, from taking civil service jobs. It also violates many norms that have superior legal authority, including the Employment Promotion Law and the International Labor Organization Convention on Nondiscrimination in Employment. Although the number of lawsuits against discrimination is increasing, there is little sanction for violations. The first landmark case was that of Zhang Xianzhu in 2002. Zhang was a 25-year-old college graduate who received the highest score on the Wuhu city (Anhui Province) civil service qualification exam but was rejected by the civil service because he tested positive for the hepatitis B virus (HBV). Zhang filed an administrative suit against the local per- sonnel bureau alleging that the rejection of HBV carriers was a discriminatory practice, which violated his fundamental constitutional rights. On April 2, 2003, the Wuhu court issued its judgment, affirming the validity of the gov- ernment regulation while ruling that the decision by the defendant to refuse to 23 Ronald Brown, China’s Employment Discrimination Laws during Economic Transition, 19 Columbia J. Asian L. 361 (Spring 2006). 24 Investigation Report on Hepatitis B Discrimination in China’s Higher Education System (Oct. 2008) by the Yirenping Center (a Chinese NGO operating in Beijing), and Investigation Report on Hepatitis B Discrimination in Multinational Corporations Based in China (Feb. 2009). 25 For further information, see Legal Protection against Employment Discrimination Handbook (Sep. 2007), and Investigation Report on Employment Discrimination in Shenzhen (May 2010). See also Lin Yanling ed., Report on Non-discrimination in Employment: Legal Systems and Practices in Asia (Social Sciences Academic Press 2010). 26 Professor Li Dun was invited by the Ministry of Health to participate in the drafting of The Regulations on HIV Prevention and Treatment. Interview with the author. Rule of Law as a Watermark 197 hire the plaintiff based on his HBV status lacked sufficient evidence. The court refused to grant Zhang’s request to enter the civil service on the ground that the recruitment period was over. However, the court failed to invalidate the discriminatory government regulation on constitutional grounds. A decade later, the judicial decision has not been enforced, but the trend in recent regu- lations regarding public hiring and university admission has mandated that physical tests for employment screening not include testing for HBV. A Weak Constitutional System In China, the lack of respect for the constitution is explained by the de facto absence of a hierarchy of norms (despite a clear theoretical definition of the “sources of the law” [ fa yuan]), resulting in confusion both in the organization and in the legal texts, administrative regulations, and decrees. It can also be explained by the lack of a clear conception of the position of the constitution in the hierarchy of the normative system, despite unambiguous terms used to designate it, such as the “fundamental law” ( genben dafa) or the “mother of all laws” (mufa). The constitution in truth is an abstract political document remote from people’s daily life and social operation. The government and the CCP have a long history of using policy rather than law to steer social development. Every change or amendment of the constitution is initiated by CCP policy changes. This practice results in pay- ing lip service to the constitution and marginalizing its legal function. The constitution then serves as a footnote to party policy and governmental prac- tice. There are numerous examples of liberties taken with the text of the con- stitution and of legal deadlock arising from social complexity and confusion of the legal system due to the absense of consensus on the effective sources of the law. The lack of respect for the constitution testifies to the historical lack of respect for the hierarchy of norms in general, due to their nonexistence in both practical and conceptual terms. However, since the Law on Legislation in 2000 established a principle of unity of the legislative system and initiated a hierarchy of norms, the constitution is theoretically at its highest position. The next challenge lies in the political courage of the government and the CCP to respect the constitution not only in words but in action.27 Another means is to entrust the Supreme People’s Court with a role that is neither recognized in the political system as a whole nor compatible with its present organization, given that the existing system is one of an a posteriori and legislative review of the constitution through the work of the National People’s Congress. While debate on constitutionalism is very rich, it has not yet been fol- lowed by any official call for open debate or adoption. Probably in May 2004, the Law and Regulation Filing Office (Fagui shencha bei’an shi) was created 27 See Cai Dingjian & Wang Chenguang, China’s Journey toward the Rule of Law: Legal Reform, 1978–2008 (Brill 2010). The World Bank Legal Review198 within the Commission for Legal Affairs (Fazhi gongzuo weiyuanhui) of the Standing Committee of the NPC. Constitutional experts have been critical of this new body whose activities and structure have remained secret. Chinese scholars hold the view that a legal apparatus is a common good through which citizens and organizations may achieve justice. They also believe in the theoretical supremacy of the constitution as a means to effec- tively check and control governmental and political power by establishing a constitutional review system. The Western concept of constitutionalism is ac- cepted academically but the political conception of a constitution as a substan- tive legal norm is not. Indeed, in Western rule of law democracies, the constitutionality of the law is intended to give rise to precise and rigorous examination. The constitu- tionality of the law is a matter of legal certainty and judicial consistency, of the practical reliability of legislative arrangements, and of democratic guarantees. Addressing the Role of Judges within the Judicial System Since 2010, judicial reform in China has been more piecemeal than systemic. It also has been oriented more toward access to justice for citizens than toward reform of the system and its actors. As in the rest of the world, litigants in China ask for much better legal services and have higher expectations than in the past. Litigants, via social networks, demand that their disputes be han- dled with greater transparency and uniformity in applying substantive and procedure law. The growing call in China that alternative dispute resolutions and mediation be viewed as intertwined with formal litigation procedures expresses a movement toward “informalizing” legal institutions. In this context, the legal profession faces many challenges in China. One is uneven geographical distribution: in 2011, there were more lawyers in Shang- hai than in the whole of Shaanxi Province, and more lawyers in the city of Shenzhen than in Fujian Province. In 2010, there were 23,000 lawyers in Bei- jing, out of a total estimated 140,000 lawyers nationwide.28 Other problems include an uneven level of professionalization and an accompanying lack of specialization (the number of defense lawyers trained every year in the coun- try is low); an absence of legal recognition of the unique capacity of lawyers to act as agents ad litem; and an inadequate representation of lawyers in courts compared to the number of judges and procuratorates. Also, lawyers’ fees re- main far too high for most litigants. Many non-lawyer legal experts act as agents ad litem in litigation procedures and lawsuits in China. Experts have shown that in China, lawyers face competition from a variety of alternative legal service providers, includ- 28 Beijing Bar Association, interviews with the author in January and May 2012. Rule of Law as a Watermark 199 ing legal workers at grassroots levels and other practitioners, presenting a challenge to the government on how to regulate these competing groups.29 Lack of trust and credibility regarding the court system are among the most pressing issues the government faces. It is important to build trust among judges and all the actors involved in courts’ management; to remain flexible with planned new reforms; and to create mechanisms for institution- alizing changes and build the conditions for achieving sustainable reforms within the judiciary.30 One of the main weaknesses of the Chinese judiciary system is the ex- tremely decentralized administration of a centralized legal system where na- tional laws tend to be abstract and local specificities are given short shrift. The role of people’s courts in the harmonization and convergence (if not unification) of legal practices must be encouraged. The main goal is to cre- ate better cooperation between and consistency of the lawmaking and judi- cial-making process to achieve a greater uniformity in the application of law and to protect citizens. People’s courts should ensure that rules are interpreted consistently throughout the country. This interpretation can be achieved only if courts are given real power and a specific status and specific tasks within the judicial system. Both legal harmonization and consistency of law enforcement require that the judicial body play both legal and moral roles. Reforms need to be oriented toward the reform of the judges’ status. Conclusion During recent decades, the Chinese legal system has undergone a fascinat- ing transformation from barely any law to a relatively comprehensive and complicated network of laws and norms. The foundations of the legal-rational state are undergoing rapid change. The law has been not only an instrument of post-socialist transition, social control, and governance but also a means of social transition and market reform in China. The concept of law is perceived as a modern means of regulation, a tool in the service of this objective. In 30 years, the rule of law rhetoric in China has moved from a concept focused on economic considerations (the Deng Xiaoping era) to one focused on maintaining stability within society and the control of the CCP (during the Hu Jintao–Wen Jiabao era). Yet, the rapid legal development cannot hide the defects in China’s legal system. Besides those mentioned above, the biggest 29 See Terence Halliday, Ethan Michelson, & Sida Liu, China’s Emerging Middle Class: Beyond Economic Transformation, ch. 14 (Cheng Li ed., Brookings Institution Press 2010). 30 See Randall Peerenboom, Economic and Social Rights: The Role of Courts in China (Oct. 17, 2010), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract _id=1693613. http://ssrn.com/abstract=http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract _id=1693613 http://ssrn.com/abstract=http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract _id=1693613 The World Bank Legal Review200 problem is that the notion of due process of law is underdeveloped because of the lack of constitutional review and the low predictability of legal outcomes. Despite ideological transformations, social changes, and radical economic reforms, the world’s second-biggest economy is not yet governed by the rule of law. Many observers in and outside China question whether rule of law is necessary for a rich, emerging country such as China. The lack of legal cer- tainty affects leadership succession processes as well as governance on a large scale and confidence in business. Demands for rule of law changes by public and legal professionals have been unprecedented. What China can achieve depends on how the legal system develops and whether the concept of the rule of law can be translated into judicial practices. What China can achieve depends largely on what China wants. 201 Achieving Development through Innovative Constitutionalism A China Story Zhenmin Wang and Yuan Tao Constitutions are created to balance political powers, to regulate the behavior of political institutions and individuals, and to protect citizens’ rights. The interplay between constitutionalism and reality constantly changes, with the evolution of a constitution the most obvious proof of that transformation. Traditionally, constitutionalism has been correlated with separation of pow- ers, limited government, and democracy. Today, however, a constitution is no longer seen as a purely political and legal document; it is also viewed as a document incorporating guiding economic principles, and growing attention is being given to the economic functions of a constitution and how consti- tutions might be used to promote economic development. Most transitional and developing nations face the challenge of proper allocation of available economic and financial resources as well as the compatibility of economic de- cisions with the constitutional framework and the limitations created by that framework. The economic function of the constitution can be used to narrow the gap between practical enforcement of the economic, social, and political rights granted by the constitution and the economic policy, budget legislation, and administrative policies conducted by the national government. Constitutions in the 18th and 19th centuries were purely political docu- ments. They had little to do with economy. The first constitution to introduce economic provisions was the 1918 Weimar Constitution of Germany. As con- stitutions have evolved, some are more focused on citizens’ rights vis-à-vis the government and private property ownership, while others provide for both political and economic affairs in a comprehensive fashion. A key challenge for modern constitutionalists, especially in developing countries, is how to use constitutional provisions to facilitate economic advancement and the devel- opment of a market economy. If a constitution can be defined as a framework of fundamental rules and principles according to which a state is governed, the locus of constitutional- ism lies at the intersection of law and politics. Every theory of constitutional- ism must take both law and policy into account and apply them in a way that is open to country-specific variations. The purpose of a constitution should be multifold: the balanced and rational allocation of governmental powers among various branches and levels; the assurance that government behavior is sub- ject to supervision and constraints; the obligation that government agencies or The World Bank Legal Review202 executive officials, whether appointed or elected, be bound by the constitution, abstain from abuse of power and corruption, and be held accountable to the people; and the protection of basic human rights and freedom. Based on this definition of a constitution, economic constitutionalism en- compasses and addresses several issues: first, what economic freedoms and rights can the constitution provide for the people; second, to what extent may the government intervene in economic affairs; and third, where does the boundary lie for government intervention in the economic arena—in other words, how does the government redistribute resources and social wealth among members of the society. The evolution of China’s constitution is an example of the changing and multifaceted nature of economic constitutionalism. The first National People’s Congress (NPC) adopted China’s first constitution in 1954. In 1975, the consti- tution was completely revised to become the second constitution. Three years later, it was rewritten and adopted as the 1978 constitution. In 1980, the Chi- nese authorities established the high-profile Constitution Revising Committee with the mandate to thoroughly review the 1978 constitution and make a new one. After two years’ consultation and deliberation, the new constitution was passed by the fifth NPC in 1982. The 1982 constitution has been amended four times: in 1988, 1993, 1999, and 2004. Most of the amendments are related to economic freedoms, especially the constitutional and legal status of private economy. As such, not only is the 1982 constitution, and its amendments, a document for legal and political affairs, but it also provides a foundation for economic development and economic justice. The 1982 constitution was adopted shortly after Deng Xiaoping took pow- er and initiated China’s “opening and reform” policy. Law played a vital role in Deng’s administration as he sought to provide greater institutional order to support China’s development. The 1982 constitution puts the constitution above all organizations in the country, including the Communist Party of Chi- na (CPC). Post-Deng leaders have modified the constitution through amend- ment, rather than replacement, preserving the continuity of economic reform ideology ushered in by Deng. Amendments have been used to constitutional- ize ideological landmarks of unfolding economic developments. For example, the constitution was revised in 1988 to make reference to a private sector to complement the “socialist public economy.” The 1993 amendments added the phrase “socialism with Chinese characteristics” to the preamble and intro- duced the “socialist market economy,” thus incorporating Deng’s economic theory into the document. A reference to the recently deceased Deng was added to the preamble in 1999. The constitution was amended in 2004 to guar- antee private property rights and provide for compensation for expropriated land, an important signal for both foreign investors and China’s own busi- ness sector. In addition, in keeping with the tradition of each Chinese leader leaving his imprint on the constitution, President Jiang Zemin introduced his theory of the “three represents” into the preamble. This provided ideological coverage for inclusion of the business class (“bourgeoisie”). Achieving Development through Innovative Constitutionalism 203 China has been the fastest-growing major economy in the world for 30 years, with an average annual growth rate above 10 percent. By 2012, as the second-largest economy in the world, China could claim that per capita income had grown at an average annual rate of more than 8 percent over the previous three decades, increasing from 379 yuan, or US$44.6, in 1978 to about US$5,184 (US$8,394 purchasing power parity, or PPP) in 2011, according to the International Monetary Fund (IMF).1 According to the World Bank, China’s economic growth fueled a decline in the poverty rate from 85 percent in 1981 to 16 percent in 2005 (poverty being defined in 2005 as the number of people living on less than US$1.25 per day).2 There are many reasons for such an economic achievement, and the con- stitution and its amendments have played a crucial role in this development. This chapter examines how a developing country such as China made such remarkable progress by enacting a new constitutional system, in particular, a new economic constitutionalism. This chapter shows how China’s economy exemplifies the development of a more traditional constitution into one that reflects many of the advantages of economic constitutionalism. The following pages trace China’s constitutional history to show this development, noting major changes that reflect innovative policies in China’s particular historical context. The Basic Economic System Established by the 1982 Constitution The political revolution that aimed to build China into a socialist country re- sulted in the founding of the People’s Republic of China in 1949. However, the 1954 constitution characterized the country as “neodemocratic” because private ownership and property rights were allowed to exist and were in fact protected. But the 1954 constitution was short-lived—it was cast aside for years, including during the 10-year “Cultural Revolution” (1966–76). Although socialist reform was completed in the late 1950s, the constitution remained unchanged until 1975. Reflecting the ultra-leftist ideology of the Cul- tural Revolution, the 1975 constitution declared that China was a “pure social- ist country.” The constitutional protection of private economy that appeared in the 1954 constitution was abolished. The 1975 constitution incorporates the protection of public ownership, eliminating all elements of private economy. As a result of the paradigm shift that took place after the Cultural Rev- olution, during the 1982 constitution-making process, a main consideration was how to build an economy-friendly constitutional system and establish a rational economic system. In its preamble, the 1982 constitution stipulates “the basic task of the nation in the years to come is to concentrate its effort on [socialist] modernization.” 1 http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Economy_of_the_People%27s_Republic_of_China. 2 Shauna Chen & Martin Ravallion, “The Developing World Is Poorer than We Thought, but No Less Successful in the Fight against Poverty (World Bank Aug. 2008). http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Economy_of_the_People%27s_Republic_of_China The World Bank Legal Review204 Public Ownership of the Means of Production and Distribution Principles Article 6 of the 1982 constitution stipulates that “the basis of the socialist eco- nomic system of the People’s Republic of China is socialist public ownership of the means of production, namely, ownership by the whole people and col- lective ownership by the working people.” Article 6 also provides for distribution principles: the system of socialist public ownership supersedes the system of exploitation of person by person; it applies the principles of “from each according to his ability” and “to each according to his work.” There are two forms of socialist public ownership mandated in the 1982 constitution. First, ownership by the whole people: Article 7 states that “the state economy is the sector of socialist economy under ownership by the whole people; it is the leading force in the national economy. The state ensures the consolidation and growth of the state economy.” Second, collective ownership by the “working people”: Article 8 provides that rural people’s communes, agricultural producers’ co-operatives, and other forms of cooperative economy such as producers’ supply and marketing, credit and consumers co-operatives, belong to the sector of socialist economy under collective ownership by the work- ing people. Working people who are members of rural economic col- lectives have the right, within the limits prescribed by law, to farm private plots of cropland and hilly land, engage in household side- line production and raise privately owned livestock. The various forms of co-operative economy in cities and towns, such as those in the handicraft, industrial, building, transport, commercial and ser- vice trades, all belong to the sector of socialist economy under collec- tive ownership by the working people. The State protects the lawful rights and interests of the urban and rural economic collectives and encourages, guides and helps the growth of the collective economy. The 1982 constitution allows for the individual economy of urban and ru- ral working people, but only as a complement to the socialist public economy. The official policy toward individual economy is that the state protects the lawful rights and interests of the individual economy. The state guides, helps, and supervises individual economy through administrative control. These provisions stem from the then-prevailing ideology that emphasized “socialist ownership” and tended to marginalize private ownership. Although the 1982 constitution does not permit Chinese citizens to run private companies, it does permit foreign enterprises, other foreign economic organizations, and individual foreigners to invest in China and to enter into various forms of economic cooperation with Chinese enterprises and other eco- nomic organizations in accordance with Chinese law. All foreign enterprises and foreign economic organizations in China, as well as joint ventures with Chinese and foreign investment located in China, must abide by the laws of China. Their lawful rights and interests are protected by the law (Article 18). Achieving Development through Innovative Constitutionalism 205 Property Rights According to Article 9 of the 1982 constitution, mineral resources, waters, forests, mountains, grassland, unreclaimed land, beaches, and other natural resources are owned by the state, that is, by the whole people, with the excep- tion of the forests, mountains, grassland, unreclaimed land, and beaches that are owned by collectives in accordance with the law. The state ensures the rational use of natural resources and protects rare animals and plants. The ap- propriation or damage of natural resources by any organization or individual by whatever means is prohibited. This provision is important for the state to maintain economic stability. Urban land is owned by the state. Land in rural and suburban areas is owned by collectives, except for those portions that belong to the state in ac- cordance with the law. House sites and private plots of cropland and hilly land are owned by collectives. The state may in the public interest take land over for its use in accordance with the law. No organization or individual may appropriate, buy, sell, or lease land or unlawfully transfer land in other ways. All organizations and individuals who use land must make rational use of the land (Article 10). The 1982 constitution emphasizes that socialist public property is sacred and inviolable (Article 12). The state protects socialist public property. Ap- propriation or damage of state or collective property by any organization or individual by whatever means is strictly prohibited. As for private ownership, Article 13 stipulates that “the state protects the right of citizens to own lawfully earned income, savings, houses, and other lawful property. The state protects by law the right of citizens to inherit pri- vate property.” Therefore, the 1982 constitution seems to suggest that citizens cannot have large-scale property such as factories or companies. Management of Economic Affairs According to the 1982 constitution, China practices economic planning on the basis of socialist public ownership, with a view to a proportionate and coor- dinated growth of the national economy by balancing economic planning and market regulation. Disruption of the state economic plan by any organization or individual is legally prohibited. Constitutions in many countries do not stipulate how to manage the econ- omy. Yet, China’s constitution has very detailed provisions on economic af- fairs. For example, Article 14 states that the state continuously raises labor productivity, improves economic re- sults and develops the productive forces by enhancing the enthusi- asm of the working people, raising the level of their technical skill, disseminating advanced science and technology, improving the sys- tems of economic administration and enterprise operation and man- agement, instituting the socialist system of responsibility in various forms, and improving organization of work. The state practices strict The World Bank Legal Review206 economy and combats waste. The state properly apportions accu- mulation and consumption, pays attention to the interests of the col- lective and the individual as well as of the state, and, on the basis of expanded production, gradually improves the material and cultural life of the people. The constitution also provides that state-owned enterprises have decision- making power in operation and management within the limits prescribed by law, on the condition that they respect the centralized leadership of the state and fulfill all their obligations under the state plan. State-owned enterprises practice democratic management through congresses of workers and staff. Collective economic organizations also enjoy decision-making power in conducting independent economic activities, on the condition that they accept the guidance of the state plan and abide by the relevant laws. Collective eco- nomic organizations practice democratic management in accordance with the law, with the entire body of their members electing or removing management and deciding on major issues concerning the operations and management of their community. Economic Freedoms and Rights The 1982 constitution provides for a wide range of freedoms and rights related to economic affairs. All citizens are equal before the law. Every citizen enjoys these rights and at the same time must perform the duties prescribed by the constitution and the law (Article 33). The 1982 constitution also recognizes that the freedom of individual citi- zens is inviolable. No citizen may be arrested except with the approval or by decision of a people’s procuratorate or by decision of a people’s court, and arrests must be made by a public security organ. Unlawful deprivation or restriction of a citizen’s freedom by detention or other means is prohibited; unlawful search of the person of citizens is also prohibited (Article 37). The in- dividual dignity of citizens is inviolable. Insult, libel, false charge, or frame-up directed against citizens by any means is prohibited (Article 38). The home of a citizen is inviolable. Unlawful search of, or intrusion into, a citizen’s home is prohibited (Article 39). The freedom and privacy of correspondence of citizens are protected by law (Article 40). In addition to the above political rights, citizens have the right as well as the duty to work. Using various channels, the state creates conditions for em- ployment, strengthens labor protection, improves working conditions, and, on the basis of expanded production, increases remuneration for work and social benefits. Work is a duty of every able-bodied citizen. The state provides necessary vocational training to citizens before they are employed (Article 42). Working people have the right to rest (Article 43). Social security is provided for under the 1982 constitution. The state pre- scribes the system of retirement for workers and staff in enterprises and un- dertakings and for functionaries of organs of the state. The livelihood of re- Achieving Development through Innovative Constitutionalism 207 tired personnel is ensured by the state and society (Article 44). Citizens have the right to material assistance from the state and society when they are old, ill, or disabled (Article 45). Citizens have the duty as well as the right to re- ceive education (Article 46). Citizens have the freedom to engage in scientific research, literary and artistic creation, and other cultural pursuits. The state encourages and assists creative endeavors conducive to the engagement in education, science, tech- nology, literature, art, and other cultural activities (Article 47). The exercise by citizens of their freedoms and rights may not infringe upon the interests of the state, society, or the collective, or upon the lawful freedoms and rights of other citizens (Article 51). Economic Reforms and Constitutional Amendments in 1988, 1993, and 1999 When the constitution was enacted in 1982, China was embarking on large- scale and wide-ranging economic reform. During the pilot phase of the re- form, various restrictions were placed on economic autonomy. For example, the original 1982 constitution did not permit citizens to own and run private companies, although it did permit foreign citizens to do so in China. A sig- nificant portion of China’s economy was still based on the state plan. The re- strictions imposed by the constitution became obstacles to economic reform. Since 1988, China has amended the constitution four times, all in the interest of further liberalizing its economy and promoting greater economic freedom. 1988 Constitutional Amendments On April 12, 1988, the seventh NPC made two constitutional amendments. One concerns private economy. It reads: The state permits the private sector of the economy to exist and de- velop within the limits prescribed by law. The private sector of the economy is a complement to the socialist public economy. The state protects the lawful rights and interests of the private sector of the economy, and exercises guidance, supervision and control over the private sector of the economy. Thus, owning and operating private businesses is legitimized, whereas some citizens were penalized before 1988 simply for owning a factory that employed seven or more employees. If a private business owner employed six or fewer helpers under the original 1982 constitution, it could fall under the “individual economy,” or sole proprietorship, which was protected by Ar- ticle 11. Therefore, this amendment, which decriminalized private economy, opened the door for the development of a market economy. The other amendment also relates to economic development. Article 10 was amended from “no organization or individual may appropriate, buy, sell, or lease land or otherwise engage in the transfer of land by unlawful means” The World Bank Legal Review208 to “no organization or individual may appropriate, buy, sell, or otherwise en- gage in the transfer of land by unlawful means. The right to the use of land may be transferred according to law.” This amendment laid out a constitu- tional foundation for the development of the real estate industry. 1993 Constitutional Amendments On March 29, 1993, the eighth NPC made more amendments to the 1982 con- stitution. One amendment states that “China is at the primary stage of socialism” and introduces “the theory of building socialism with Chinese characteristics.” This amendment provides a rationale for promoting a private and market- oriented economy. A more fundamental change was introduced with another amendment. Article 15 was amended from The state practices economic planning on the basis of socialist public ownership. It ensures the proportionate and coordinated growth of the national economy through overall balancing by economic plan- ning and the supplementary role of regulation by the market. Dis- turbance of the orderly functioning of the social economy or disrup- tion of the State economic plan by any organization or individual is prohibited to the state has put into practice a socialist market economy. The state strengthens formulating economic laws, improves macro adjust- ment and control and forbids according to law any units or indi- viduals from interfering with the social economic order. According to this amendment, the economy in China is no longer a planned economy but a market-oriented one, even though many Western countries still do not recognize the market economy status of China. 1999 Constitutional Amendments On March 15, 1999, China again proposed a sweeping set of constitutional amendments. Seven amendments were passed altogether. Important changes to the economic system include the following. • Deng Xiaoping theory was incorporated into the constitution as state guidance, in addition to Marxism-Leninism and Mao Zedong thought. • It was acknowledged that “China will stay in the primary stage of social- ism for a long period of time.” • Rule of law was officially introduced for the first time. Article 5 was added: “The People’s Republic of China practices ruling the country in accor- dance with the law and building a socialist country under rule of law.” Achieving Development through Innovative Constitutionalism 209 • Article 6, which covers the economic system, was amended from The basis of the socialist economic system of the People’s Republic of China is socialist public ownership of the means of production, namely, ownership by the whole people and collective ownership by the working people. . . . The system of socialist public ownership supersedes the system of exploitation of man by man; it applies the principle of “from each according to his ability, to each according to his work.” to The basis of the socialist economic system of the People’s Republic of China is socialist public ownership of the means of production, namely, ownership by the whole people and collective ownership by the working people. The system of socialist public ownership su- persedes the system of exploitation of man by man; it applies the principle of “from each according to his ability, to each according to his work.” . . . During the primary stage of socialism, the state adheres to the basic economic system with the public ownership remaining dominant and diverse sectors of the economy developing side by side, and to the distribution system with the distribution according to work remaining dominant and the coexistence of a variety of modes of distribution. • Article 11, on private economy, was amended from The individual economy of urban and rural working people, oper- ating within the limits prescribed by law, is a complement to the socialist public economy. The state protects the lawful rights and interests of the individual economy. . . . The state guides, helps and supervises the individual economy by exercising administrative control. . . . The state permits the private economy to exist and de- velop within the limits prescribed by law. The private economy is a complement to the socialist public economy. The state protects the lawful rights and interests of the private economy, and guides, su- pervises and administers the private economy. to Individual, private, and other nonpublic economies that exist within the limits prescribed by law are major components of the socialist market economy. . . . The state protects the lawful rights and inter- ests of individual and private economies, and guides, supervises, and administers individual and private economies. Thus, the status of the nonpublic economy was endorsed by official con- stitutional amendments. The World Bank Legal Review210 2004 Constitutional Amendments The 2004 constitutional amendments are significant. From “Socialism with Chinese Characteristics” to “Chinese-Style Socialism” In the preamble, “along the road of building socialism with Chinese character- istics” was revised to “along the road of Chinese-style socialism.” This seem- ingly editorial change means that the socialism in China is “made in China,” not imported from another country or copied from textbooks. This change has been widely interpreted to mean that the development model in China is unique in nature, neither capitalist nor conventionally socialist. Both capitalist and traditional socialist models have their merits and demerits. In this amend- ment, China recognizes the value of both systems. How China develops its own model will be based on Chinese circumstances and the current world sit- uation, rather than on transplanting economic systems from other countries. The Three Represents In the preamble, “under the guidance of Marxism-Leninism, Mao Zedong thought, and Deng Xiaoping theory” was revised to “under the guidance of Marxism-Leninism, Mao Zedong thought, Deng Xiaoping theory, and the im- portant thought of ‘three represents.’ ” This change is more than merely political window dressing. Since 1988, when a constitutional amendment first green-lighted private economy, the private sector has undergone substantial development. By 2004, the private sector dominated the local economy in many coastal provinces. Historically, however, according to the constitution, China was a country for workers and farmers, not the bourgeoisie. The Chinese government constitutionally did not represent nonpublic sectors. The “three represents” means that the party and the state (government) must always represent the development trend of China’s advanced productive forces, the orientation of China’s advanced culture, and the fundamental interests of the majority of the Chinese people. Thus, the Chinese Communist Party and the government also represent the private sector and the business class. According to this amendment, China is not only a country for workers and farmers but also a country for the emerging private sector. This ideology will guide the party and the government for years. State Compensation for Land Expropriated or Requisitioned Article 10 was amended from “The state may, in the public interest, requisition land for its use in accordance with the law” to “The state may, in the public interest and in accordance with the provisions of law, expropriate or requisi- tion land for its use and shall make compensation for the land expropriated or requisitioned.” Achieving Development through Innovative Constitutionalism 211 Protection of Lawful Rights and Interests of the Nonpublic Sectors Article 11 was amended from “the state protects the lawful rights and inter- ests of the individual and private sectors of the economy, and exercises guid- ance, supervision, and control over individual and the private sectors of the economy” to The state protects the lawful rights and interests of the nonpublic sectors of the economy such as the individual and private sectors of the economy. The state encourages, supports, and guides the devel- opment of the nonpublic sectors of the economy and, in accordance with law, exercises supervision and control over the nonpublic sec- tors of the economy. Citizens’ Lawful Private Property Is Inviolable Article 13 was amended from “The state protects the right of citizens to own lawfully earned income, savings, houses, and other lawful property” and “The state protects according to law the right of citizens to inherit private property” to “Citizens’ lawful private property is inviolable”; “The state, in accordance with law, protects the rights of citizens to private property and to its inheritance”; and “The state may, in the public interest and in accordance with law, expropriate or requisition private property for its use and shall make compensation for the private property expropriated or requisitioned.” For the first time, a socialist constitution explicitly provides for the protec- tion of private property. Social Security System In 2004, China added to Article 14: “The state establishes a sound social secu- rity system compatible with the level of economic development.” Human Rights China added Article 33: “The state respects and preserves human rights.” This is the first time that the Chinese constitution has formally recognized the val- ue of human rights. Conclusion The multifarious nature of constitutionalism has inspired different under- standings of the meaning of “constitutionalism.” Adding to this confusion is the inevitable disparity between what is contained in the text of a constitu- tion and how those provisions are implemented. By all accounts, however, progressive economic constitutionalism has contributed to China’s change in one generation from a poverty-stricken country to one of the world’s largest economies. While China has been learning from the rest of the world, it has established its own way of development based on its unique circumstances. The World Bank Legal Review212 China’s experience shows that constitutional changes and economic re- forms are intertwined and that they should be coordinated in a gradual and pragmatic manner. It took many years for China to recognize and accept con- cepts such as private economy, market economy, private property rights, hu- man rights, and rule of law. There is no statically ideal constitution in any dynamically changing society; constitutionalism does not mean that there must be a perfect constitution before its practice. Perhaps there is no perfect constitution—constitutional development is a never-ending process. Ultimately, a constitution resides in the particular historical and circum- stantial settings of its country. One country can draw experiences from other countries, but it is impossible to transplant a constitutional system completely. To achieve national modernization, democracy alone is not adequate; it must be governed by constitutionalism and rule of law. The presence or ab- sence of constitutionalism and rule of law is crucial to the success or failure of democracy. The development of democracy and constitutionalism can be cate- gorized into two models: the success of the British-American model lies in the establishment of constitutionalism and rule of law in the first place, followed by democracy under a ready and stable constitutional and legal framework; while the French model aimed to introduce full democracy first and establish constitutionalism and rule of law later. Either way, to emphasize constitution- alism does not mean to ignore the development of democracy, or vice versa. A synergetic coordination of constitutionalism and rule of law is the ultimate goal for China. The past and current financial crises have proved that a free market economy is not omnipotent. Government involvement and redistribution of resources and social wealth are not always counterproductive. Early consti- tutions in Western countries established a completely free market economy system, which was suspicious and hostile toward government intervention. As the recent crisis has shown, however, a modern constitution should give the government reasonable powers to regulate the market economy and al- locate social resources. This has nothing to do with ideology—it is a matter of distributive justice and social administration. Daniel Webster wrote, “One country, one constitution, one destiny.”3 To a great extent, the nature of a country’s constitution determines the destiny of the country. From the Chinese legal perspective, a constitution not only reflects the country’s economic base but also contributes to the economic base. As such, the constitution in China is not only the supreme law of the state but also an active social, economic, and political program for social transforma- tion and development. 3 From a speech of March 15, 1837; reported in Edward Everett ed., The Works of Daniel Webster 349 (Little, Brown 1853). 213 The Role of Laws and Institutions in Expanding Women’s Voice, Agency, and Empowerment Jeni Klugman and Sarah Twigg “Voice, agency, and empowerment” refers to the ability of individuals and groups to make effective choices. Across all countries, the ability of women and men to exercise voice and agency differs—and women are usually at a disadvantage. The World Development Report 2012: Gender Equality and Devel- opment (WDR 2012)1 highlights the vital importance of women’s voice and agency in both the household and society in general. This report—a landmark for the World Bank because it recognizes both the intrinsic and instrumental values of women’s voice, agency, and empowerment—identifies shrinking gender differences in voice and agency as a policy priority for future action. Voice, agency, and empowerment have intrinsic value for women’s in- dividual well-being and quality of life; they are valuable ends in their own right. This concept is in line with Amartya Sen’s view of development as the process of enlarging a person’s ‘‘functionings and capabilities to function, the range of things that a person could do and be in her life.”2 But the WDR 2012 also shows that these goals are instrumental in achieving sustainable social and economic development. When women and men have equal voice and participation in public life, significant societal benefits result. For example, public health spending in the United States increased dramatically in the early 1920s after women won the right to vote. Women’s participation in politics led to an intensive scaling up of hygiene campaigns and a sharp decline in child mortality. It is estimated that roughly 20,000 child deaths were averted every year because women won the right to vote, which explains about 10 percent of the reduction in child mortality in the United States between 1900 and 1930.3 What roles do laws play in fostering women’s voice, agency, and empower- ment? Laws formalize individual and collective rights and provide the frame- work within which people are empowered to exercise their voice and agency. Laws and their effective implementation and enforcement can be especially The views expressed in this article are solely those of the authors and do not reflect those of the World Bank or its Executive Directors. The authors are grateful to Humay Gulyieva for assistance and Tazeen Hasan for comments. 1 World Bank, World Development Report 2012: Gender Equality and Development (World Bank 2012) (hereinafter, WDR 2012). 2 A. Sen, Development as Capability Expansion, 17 J. of Dev. Planning 41–58 (1989). 3 Grant Miller, Women’s Suffrage, Political Responsiveness, and Child Survival in American History (Stanford Medical School & NBER 2007). The World Bank Legal Review214 important for disadvantaged individuals and groups as they try to overcome underlying discrimination and structural inequalities—although laws some- times serve to further entrench disadvantage and existing inequalities. The interaction between laws on the one hand and voice and agency on the other is mutually reinforcing. Changes in agency, patriarchal attitudes, and social norms can be important triggers for changes in laws, as evidenced by the significant role played by women’s collective movements since 1975 in promoting more egalitarian family laws in 70 countries around the world.4 At the same time, the very act of bestowing the stamp of legality, or illegality, has been a catalyst for increasing agency and transforming attitudes when intro- duced as part of a multisectoral package. As Martin Luther King declared, “It may be true that the law cannot make a man love me. . . . But if it keeps him from lynching me, I think that’s pretty important also.”5 There has been some progress in recognizing women’s equality and wom- en’s rights at the international level. The Convention to Eliminate All Forms of Discrimination Against Women (CEDAW), agreed upon in Mexico in 1975, has been a pioneering instrument of human rights for women. It addressed for the first time discrimination in the private sphere, including the extension of protection to women against family violence, and sought to tackle substantive inequalities. To this end, CEDAW recognized the centrality of eliminating all forms of discrimination in order to achieve equality for women; it articulated the need to eliminate prejudices, customary practices, social norms, and ste- reotyped roles for men and women; and it focused on achieving equality of outcomes, that is, equality in real terms.6 There are many examples of CEDAW helping to win tangible gains for girls and women, as in India, where the Supreme Court in 1997 relied on CEDAW to draw up a set of guidelines and norms for the processing of sexual harassment complaints.7 This chapter, building on the evidence and insights presented in the WDR 2012, reviews the potential power of laws to expand women’s voice and agency. The analysis follows the framework set out in the WDR 2012, which finds that limited progress in women’s agency is explained by mutually reinforcing con- straints in markets, formal institutions, and informal institutions (see figure 1). This points to the need to systematically analyze the interplay of these sectors. The focus of this chapter is confined to the role of formal and informal laws. 4 Mala Htun and S. Laurel Weldon, Communism, Colonialism and Clerical Power: Historical Lega- cies and Feminist Activism in the Struggle over Family Law (Harvard U. 2011). 5 Dr. Martin Luther King, Jr. Towards Freedom, speech given at Dartmouth College (May 23, 1962). 6 For broader discussion of the significance of CEDAW for women’s rights and gender equal- ity see Richard Jolly, Louis Emmerij, & Thomas G. Weiss, UN Ideas That Changed the World (United Nations 2009). 7 Vishaka and others v. State of Rajasthan and others (AIR 1997 SUPREME COURT 3011) J.S. Verma C.J.I., Mrs. Sujata V. Manohar, & B.N. Kirpal, JJ. Expanding Women’s Voice, Agency, and Empowerment 215 Figure 1. Limited Progress in Women’s Agency Is Explained by Mutually Reinforcing Constraints in Markets, Formal Institutions, and Informal Institutions Source: WDR 2012, 153. The chapter begins by outlining the pathways through which laws affect women’s empowerment and their ability to exercise voice and agency, fol- lowed by a review of the role of plural legal systems and customary and reli- gious laws. It then investigates the reality of laws in practice, which includes looking at issues such as access to justice and enforcement of laws, and closes with a discussion of the role of social norms in shaping or constraining the application of laws. Pathways through Which Laws Enhance Women’s Ability to Exercise Voice and Agency Laws formalize individual and collective rights and provide the framework within which people exercise agency. Progress has been made globally in re- forming legislative and constitutional frameworks to advance gender equal- ity and women’s rights. A nondiscrimination clause covering gender now appears in the constitutions of 97 countries, and 132 countries have constitu- tional guarantees of equality before the law. Yet many countries still have legal provisions that overtly discriminate against women in both statutory and customary law, sometimes in the consti- tution and sometimes despite what the constitution requires. Indeed, in 47 of the countries with constitutional equality provisions, legislation on access to institutions means women are less able than men to interact with public au- thorities and the private sector. This includes restrictions on a woman’s ability to get a job, sign a contract, register a business, open a bank account, be the The World Bank Legal Review216 head of the household, or choose where to live.8 According to Women, Busi- ness, and the Law, of the 53 countries studied that formally recognize custom- ary or religious law as valid sources of law under the constitution, more than half exempt such laws from constitutional provisions on nondiscrimination or equality.9 This discrepancy reveals a disconnect between constitutionally pro- tected rights and statutory and customary law, which affects what plays out in practice. In the Democratic Republic of Congo, for example, the constitution expressly prohibits discrimination on the basis of gender and provides for equality before the law; yet married women cannot get a job, sign a contract, register a business, or be the head of a household in the same way as men. The constitution does not invalidate customary law that is discriminatory or in conflict with constitutional provisions of equality. Family laws, laws related to gender-based violence, and laws related to economic opportunities are among the domains of law most likely to limit women’s empowerment; these are discussed briefly below. In some countries, women’s citizenship rights are limited—a woman cannot confer citizenship on a foreign spouse in the same way as a man in 35 countries, and in 20 of those, women cannot confer citizenship on their children.10 Restrictions can limit women’s mobility and access to work. Countries such as the Islamic Republic of Iran, Saudi Arabia, Sudan, and the Republic of Yemen, where married women are required to have male permission to travel or to work outside the home, show how the law itself can restrict wom- en’s agency. One result of this restriction is very low rates of female labor force participation—ranging from as low as 20 percent (Yemen) to 32 percent (Iran)—compared with male labor force participation of 73 percent (Iran) to 80 percent (Saudi Arabia). Legal disparities can reduce women’s ability to participate on an equal footing with men in the economy. Women, Business, and the Law finds that greater lack of legal gender parity in business and institutional laws is associ- ated with lower labor force participation by women (both in absolute terms and relative to men) and lower levels of women’s entrepreneurship. This is supported by a study in Africa that found that gender gaps in legal capacity and property rights limited women’s roles as entrepreneurs. The gap between the share of women and men who are employers is 30 percent higher in coun- tries where there are larger gender disparities in economic rights.11 8 World Bank, Women, Business, and the Law 2012: Removing Barriers to Economic Inclusion (International Bank for Reconstruction and Development/The World Bank 2012) (herein- after, WBL). 9 Twenty-seven countries do not consider customary or personal law as invalid if the law violates constitutional provisions on nondiscrimination or equality; id. 10 WBL, supra note 8. 11 M. Hallward-Driemeier & T. Hasan, Empowering Women: Legal Rights and Opportunities in Africa, World Bank Africa Development Forum Series (2012). Expanding Women’s Voice, Agency, and Empowerment 217 Women’s collective voice in society is a critical component of the full ex- ercise of empowerment and agency. There are many examples of women’s groups at the local level and movements at the national and global level en- abling voice and affecting change. Perhaps one of the better-known examples is the Self-Employed Women’s Association in India (SEWA), which represents the interests of a large number of informal sector workers and entrepreneurs. SEWA provides information, support, and training services to its members; offers a platform for voicing concerns; and has created space for public action through which women workers have actively challenged their employers and the state.12 A major campaign in 2003 in support of better wages for incense stick rollers resulted in around half of all workers (10,000 women) receiving an increase in pay; another 2,000 were able to restart working after having re- ceived training in new techniques.13 In situations like this, the legal framework is key—in Ethiopia, where the framework for civil society has been tightened since 2009, civil society organizations are unable to receive foreign funding if they engage in any work pertaining to human rights. The Ethiopian Women Lawyers Association (EWLA) is one civil society organization whose work has been affected. EWLA provided free legal aid to more than 17,000 women in 2008 and supported other activities that tens of thousands of participants benefited from. As a result of the legislation passed in 2009, EWLA cut back services, which now are restricted to limited legal aid for women provided by volunteers.14 For their voices to be transformative, women need to be present when and where decisions are made—in parliament, legal institutions, formal pro- fessional institutions, and local and state governments. Yet, women make up only 19 percent of parliamentarians worldwide, and in some regions their presence is even lower. In the Middle East and North Africa, women are only 1 in 10 parliamentarians, and in Papua New Guinea there is only 1 female parliamentarian.15 Quotas, while sometimes controversial, can be an effective means of im- proving women’s representation. More than half of the countries in the world have implemented some type of political quota, in the form of voluntary quo- tas by parties on electoral lists, reservation of a certain share of candidate po- sitions for women, or reservation of a share of legislative slots. The use of such quotas has led to a dramatic increase in female leaders across the globe. Voluntary party quotas, for example, currently in place in 51 countries, can both reflect and fuel changes in public attitudes and signify a commitment 12 WDR 2012, supra note 1. 13 J. Blaxall, India’s Self-Employed Women’s Association (SEWA). Empowerment through Mobiliza- tion of Poor Women on a Large Scale: A Case Study from Reducing Poverty, Sustaining Growth; What Works, What Doesn’t, and Why: A Global Exchange for Scaling Up Success (World Bank 2012). 14 Amnesty International (Mar. 11, 2012), available at http://www.amnestyusa.org/news /news-item/ethiopia-human-rights-work-crippled-by-restrictive-law. 15 Inter Parliamentary Union, available at http://www.ipu.org/wmn-e/world.htm. http://www.amnestyusa.org/news/news-item/ethiopia-human-rights-work-crippled-by-restrictive-law http://www.ipu.org/wmn-e/world.htm http://www.amnestyusa.org/news/news-item/ethiopia-human-rights-work-crippled-by-restrictive-law The World Bank Legal Review218 to gender equality, which also contributes to higher levels of female partici- pation. Mandatory quotas in the form of reserved legislative seats have had positive results for women’s representation and participation in South Asia and parts of Africa. In Rwanda, where the constitution stipulates a 30 percent quota for women members of parliament, this number has been far exceeded: women now make up 56 percent of the lower house and 39 percent of the up- per house.16 This change has translated into legislative gains for women in the form of revised family and inheritance laws, for example, and women report increased respect from family and community members, enhanced capacity to speak and be heard in public forums, greater autonomy in decision making in the family, and increased access to education.17 The same is true in the private sector. Women have low representation on the boards of large firms (around 12 percent in Europe, 10 percent in the Americas, 7 percent in Asia and the Pacific, and 3 percent in the Middle East and North Africa). Quotas can be one way to tackle that representation. Nor- way was the first country to introduce legislated corporate quotas in 2003, prior to which female representation had increased slowly. Female board rep- resentation jumped rapidly from around 16 percent in 2004 to the mandated 40 percent in 2008. In Australia, the prospect of reform had a positive effect on women’s participation. In 2011, the Australian Stock Exchange (ASX) Corpo- rate Governance Council implemented a diversity policy requiring all publicly listed companies in Australia to set gender-diversity targets. Anticipation of the reforms had a positive impact on women in ASX leadership—which saw a 600 percent increase in new women board appointees between 2009 and 2010 (increasing from 5 percent to 27 percent).18 Yet there have been some unexpected negative consequences of quotas. Reports from Rwanda suggest there has been some withdrawal of men from politics, increased marital discord, and a perception that marriage as an in- stitution has been disrupted by the upheaval of gender roles.19 In Pakistan, quotas that violated strong social norms have been associated with increased discrimination of women.20 We now turn to look more closely at three key domains of law that af- fect women’s voice and agency: family law, which is an underlying building block; laws regulating domestic and gender-based violence; and laws regulat- ing women’s economic rights. 16 International Parliamentary Union, available at http://www.ipu.org/wmn-e/classif.htm. 17 J. Burnet, Women Have Found Respect: Gender Quotas, Symbolic Representation and Female Em- powerment in Rwanda, 7(3) Politics and Gender 303–34 (2011). 18 Australian Human Rights Commission, available at http://www.hreoc.gov.au/sex_dis crimination/programs/women_leadership.html. 19 Burnet, supra note 17. 20 Mona Lina Krook, The Diffusion of Electoral Reform: Gender Quotas in Global Perspective, paper presented at the European Consortium for Political Research, Lisbon (2009). http://www.hreoc.gov.au/sex_discrimination/programs/women_leadership.html http://www.ipu.org/wmn-e/classif.htm http://www.hreoc.gov.au/sex_discrimination/programs/women_leadership.html Expanding Women’s Voice, Agency, and Empowerment 219 Family Law Laws that regulate relations within the household play a significant role in fos- tering or restricting women’s empowerment and agency. Legislation directed at domestic relations between men and women can lead the way in chang- ing social attitudes. But change on this front has been slow. According to the WDR 2012, progress in law reform has been the slowest in areas that regulate household relations (family laws). Major inequalities still exist in inheritance rights; 26 countries have statutory inheritance laws that differentiate between women and men.21 These inequalities have serious negative consequences for women’s empowerment because inheritance is often a key way to accumulate assets. They can also have serious consequences in terms of impoverishment of widows.22 Land laws and laws around land titling are important for access to assets, especially for female farmers and entrepreneurs. Joint ownership in marriage, for example, increases women’s ability to use land in accessing economic op- portunities, while mandatory joint land titling has the added benefit of pro- tecting a wife’s rights to land in the event of her husband’s death. Evaluations are under way to help document how much difference these policies make in practice. In many countries, women and girls still have fewer inheritance rights than men and boys. All Organization for Economic Cooperation and Devel- opment (OECD) countries, the former Soviet Union, and Latin America re- formed their inheritance laws more than 50 years ago to reflect more equal distribution, while in other regions the picture is mixed. All 14 countries from the Middle East and North Africa included in Women, Business, and the Law have differential inheritance rights for women as compared to men, as well as 7 in Sub-Saharan Africa, 3 in South Asia, and 2 in East Asia and the Pacific. In majority-Muslim countries, important doctrinal differences affect the extent to which females and males inherit equally. In Turkey, for example, inheritance rights for girls and boys have long been equal in law and in practice, while in Bangladesh, the law provides for unequal inheritance rights, albeit with the option for families to agree on more equal distribution. Law reform to improve women’s inheritance rights could provide an ef- fective means to reduce gender discrimination and improve a wide range of socioeconomic outcomes for women. There are some solid examples of re- form. In Rwanda, following reforms to inheritance laws in 1999 that provided for women’s equal inheritance rights with men, land tenure reform was passed in 2004 to ensure that Rwandan men and women have secure title for 21 Countries included in Women, Business, and the Law with gender-unequal inheritance laws are Bangladesh, Burundi, the Arab Republic of Egypt, Guinea, Indonesia, the Islamic Repub- lic of Iran, Kuwait, Lebanon, Malaysia, Mali, Mauritania, Morocco, Nepal, Oman, Pakistan, Saudi Arabia, Senegal, Sudan, the Syrian Arab Republic, Tanzania, Tunisia, the United Arab Emirates, West Bank and Gaza, and the Republic of Yemen. See WBL, supra note 8. 22 See D. van de Walle, Welfare Effects of Widowhood in a Poor Country (World Bank 2011). The World Bank Legal Review220 their land. The law provides that new land titles for couples include the names of both the husband and the wife and that girls are able to inherit land from their parents in the same way as boys.23 In India, law reforms at the state level that eliminated gender discrimination in inheritance rights resulted in delays in the age of marriage for girls and improvements in girls’ education—girls’ mean years of schooling increased by between 11 and 25 percent following the reforms in 1994.24 UN Women’s 2011–2012 Progress of the World’s Women Report notes that, his- torically, legal jurisdiction was divided between public and private matters, leaving the private sphere of the family and intimate relationships outside formal justice systems. The seeming resistance by governments to step into the private sphere to regulate personal relations is reflected in the reservations demonstrated by many countries in signing on to CEDAW. Out of the 187 coun- tries that have ratified CEDAW, 29 have registered reservations to Article 16, which calls for the elimination of all forms of discrimination in all matters relating to family and marriage relations. In many cases, reservations exist because family laws are subject to discriminatory plural legal provisions—an issue discussed in greater detail below. In a number of countries, the act of marriage weakens a woman’s legal and property rights—married women cannot legally choose where to live in 23 countries, married women do not have the same legal ownership rights to movable and immovable property as men (or unmarried women) in 7 coun- tries, and married women cannot apply for a passport in the same way as men (or unmarried women) in 20 countries.25 Marital property regimes that allow a woman to leave a marriage with a significant or equal share of household assets can increase her bargaining power, even if she never exercises that right.26 Conversely, laws restricting a woman’s options for exiting a marriage, such as those that leave her finan- cially insecure in cases of divorce, can limit her agency and bargaining power within the family. Changing these laws can have a dramatic impact, as seen in the United States: domestic violence fell about 30 percent between 1970 and 1990 after equitable divorce laws were introduced.27 Laws that constrain a woman’s mobility limit options for extended social and support networks and restrict her ability to leave in the case of disagreement, violence, or abuse. In 20 countries covered by Women, Business, and the Law, married women cannot apply for a passport in the same way as a man; and in 4 countries, a married 23 OECD, Women’s Economic Empowerment Issues (DAC Network on Gender Equality 2011). 24 Klaus Deininger, Aparajita Goyal, & Hari Naharajan, Inheritance Law Reform and Women’s Access to Capital: Evidence from India’s Hindu Succession Act, Policy Research Working Paper No. 5338 (World Bank 2010). 25 WBL, supra note 8. 26 WDR 2012, supra note 1. 27 Betsey Stevenson & Justin Wolfers, Bargaining in the Shadow of the Law: Divorce Laws and Family Distress, 121 Quarterly Journal of Economics 267–88 (Feb. 2006). Expanding Women’s Voice, Agency, and Empowerment 221 woman legally cannot travel outside her home or outside the country in the same way as a man. Yet, these numbers capture only formal statutory restric- tions; the numbers are much larger when one considers customary laws. Laws that set a minimum age for marriage are important. Yet in 50 countries, the minimum legal age of marriage is lower for females than for males28—as low as 14 years in Mexico, Mozambique, and Venezuela.29 Early marriage exposes girls to early pregnancy and childbirth, increases their risk of contracting HIV/AIDS, and can limit opportunities for education.30 For ex- ample, only 2 percent of married girls between the ages of 15 and 19 in Nigeria attend school, compared with 69 percent of their unmarried female peers.31 Figure 2. Discrimination in Social Institutions Impedes Women’s Education and Literacy Source: OECD SIGI, 2009. The OECD’s Social Institutions and Gender Index (SIGI) captures criti- cal societal norms and institutions that affect how women fare—using family code, physical integrity, son preference, civil liberties, and ownership rights— and is applied to 102 developing countries. Figure 2 shows that countries with high levels of discrimination in social institutions have a lower ratio of 28 UN Statistics Division (2010), “UNdata,” http://data.un.org, as cited in UN Women (2011– 2012). 29 http://data.un.org/Data.aspx?d=GenderStat&f=inID:19 (accessed Apr. 30, 2012). 30 S. Clark, Protecting Young Women from HIV/AIDS: The Case against Child and Adolescent Mar- riage (International Family Planning Perspectives Jun. 2006). 31 Gordon and Sarah Brown Foundation, Out of Wedlock into School: A Review by Gordon Brown (Office of Gordon and Sarah Brown 2012). http://data.un.org http://data.un.org/Data.aspx?d=GenderStat&f=inID:19 The World Bank Legal Review222 female to male literacy rates; that is, women are less literate compared to men in countries with high levels of social institutional discrimination, while those countries where discrimination is lower are closer to parity in education.32 The causality can run in both directions. Evidence from Turkey shows that extending compulsory education age by three years reduced the proportion of 16-year-old girls who were married by 44 percent, and those who had given birth by age 17 by 36 percent.33 Yet, even when countries reform their laws toward more equal treatment of men and women, differences can persist. The amendment of inheritance law reform in India resulted in a range of benefits for girls, as noted above, but it did not fully eliminate the underlying inequality in girls’ access to inherited land.34 This discrepancy may be due in part to a lack of dissemination of infor- mation on the changed legal provisions. Laws are also sometimes ignored or weakly enforced, or they may be circumvented. Laws Regulating Domestic and Gender-Based Violence Gender-based violence both reflects and reinforces inequities between men and women and damages the health, dignity, security, and autonomy of its vic- tims. It is inextricably linked to gender inequality and perpetuates male power and control, in particular when it takes place within the home. Paragraph 12 of the Beijing Declaration and Platform for Action codifies this message, stating: “Violence against women both violates and impairs or nullifies the enjoyment by women of their human rights and fundamental freedoms.” Violence against women, much of which occurs in the private domain, has not been widely legislated against until recently. But significant progress has been made—as of April 2011, 125 countries had passed legislation on domestic violence, and almost two-thirds of countries, in efforts to make workplaces and public spaces safer for women, had passed laws on sexual harassment.35 The Protocol to the African Charter on Human and Peoples’ Rights on the Rights of Women in Africa reflects progress in this area. The protocol states that “parties shall prohibit and condemn all forms of harmful practices which negatively affect the human rights of women and which are contrary to recog- nized international standards.”36 32 The SIGI is calculated based on the following indicators: early marriage, polygamy, parental authority, inheritance, female genital mutilation, violence against women, freedom of move- ment, freedom of dress, access to land, access to credit, and access to property other than land. 33 Murat G. Kirdar, Meltem Dayıoğlu Tayfur, & İsmet Koç, The Effect of Compulsory Schooling Laws on Teenage Marriage and Births in Turkey, Institute for the Study of Labor Discussion Paper No. 5887 ( July 2011). 34 Deininger, Goyal, & Naharajan, supra note 24. 35 UN Women (2011–2012), supra note 28, at Annex 4. 36 African Union, Protocol to the African Charter on Human and People’s Rights on the Rights of Women in Africa, paragraph 5 (2003). Expanding Women’s Voice, Agency, and Empowerment 223 Yet, many penal and civil law codes fail to criminalize certain kinds of physical, sexual, or emotional violence. As a result, domestic violence sta- tistics around the world are horrifying: at least 1 of every 10 ever-partnered women is physically or sexually assaulted by an intimate partner or someone she knows at some point in her life.37 Progress in legislating to prevent vio- lence against women has been uneven across regions. The Middle East and North Africa in particular lag behind in legislating against all forms of vio- lence against women—no country in the region has legislation criminalizing marital rape, less than 20 percent of the region has legislation against domestic violence, and just over 20 percent of countries have legislation against sexual harassment. Other regions are more varied—less than 40 percent of countries in East Asia and the Pacific have legislation against sexual harassment, and 37 WDR 2012, supra note 1. World Bank Efforts to Improve Women’s Land Rights Foster Empowerment and Agency In recognition of the importance of property rights in fostering women’s empow- erment and agency, the World Bank has been working with local authorities in some areas to facilitate more equal property ownership. In Aceh, Indonesia, where the 2004 tsunami affected 800 kilometers of coast- line and destroyed close to 53,800 parcels of land, the Bank integrated gender into its post-tsunami reconstruction efforts. The land administration system sus- tained significant damage—documentation of land ownership was washed away, one-third of the National Land Agency’s staff were killed, and physical boundary markers disappeared. The impact on women was particularly grave, because the tsunami deprived them of the safety nets offered by families, especially spouses and parents. In Aceh, land issues are traditionally considered to be the “natural” dominion of men, and this norm is reinforced by the lack of female representation on local committees and the absence of gender-disaggregated data. The Reconstruction of Aceh Land Administration System (RALAS) project integrated a well-functioning and gender-informed approach to land and prop- erty rights by introducing joint titling and recording gender in the official register. Neither of these practices existed before. Considering that more than 275,000 land parcels have been registered during RALAS, the recording of gender is a signifi- cant step forward. In addition, RALAS has been engaged in the promotion of women’s land rights by advocacy and policy dissemination with the study Gender Impacts of Land Titling in Aceh. The experience in Aceh has informed the work of reconstruction teams in Haiti, who recognize that taking gender-related factors into account in land administration can diffuse tensions over identity, status, and power that may threaten peace and security in postconflict situations. The World Bank Legal Review224 just over 40 percent of countries in South Asia and Sub-Saharan Africa have legislation against domestic violence.38 Violence against women and girls perpetrated by family members also remains largely outside the law. Rape within marriage is illegal in only one- third of all countries.39 Even where legislation exists, societal norms may result in persistently high rates of domestic violence. These norms may be widely shared by women and men. In too many countries—including Burkina Faso, Ethiopia, Guinea, Mali, Morocco, and Sierra Leone—more than half of women think it is acceptable for a man to beat his wife when they argue.40 Laws Regulating Women’s Participation in the Economy Women make up only 41 percent of the total workforce in the formal sector and tend to be concentrated in lower-paid and lower-status jobs.41 Evidence suggests that laws explain part of this disparity. Laws can restrict a woman’s participation in the economy, including restrictions on working hours, the sec- tors in which a woman can work, and mandates requiring lower retirement ages for women. Women, Business, and the Law documents 44 countries that restrict the working hours of women and 71 that limit the industries in which women can work relative to men. These restrictions are evident across all in- come levels and all regions of the world—this is not just a developing-country phenomenon. Statutory provision for child care and maternity leave and benefits, along- side the recognition of flexi-time or part-time work, can improve women’s participation in the labor force. In Latin America, 19 of the 20 countries in- cluded in Women, Business, and the Law legally require the state to provide or subsidize child care. These mandates can translate into available and afford- able child care, as in Colombia, where the government’s Hogares Comuni- tarios program pays women a small fee to take care of other women’s children and provides the caregiver food to feed the children three times a day.42 Yet, in Guatemala and Mexico, notwithstanding the legal obligation of the state to provide or subsidize child care, the lack of available care often pushes women into informal employment, and in Peru, 40 percent of working mothers take their children to work.43 The availability of part-time or flexible work can increase women’s partici- pation in the labor force, particularly women with young children. In Argen- 38 UN Women (2011–2012), supra note 28, at Annex 4. 39 WDR 2012, supra note 1. 40 WDR 2012, supra note 1. 41 WBL, supra note 8. 42 Orazio Attanasio and Marcos Vera-Hernandez, Medium and Long-Run Effects of Nutrition and Child Care: Evaluation of a Community Nursery Programme in Rural Colombia (Centre for the Evaluation of Development Policies, Institute for Fiscal Studies EWP04/06 2006). 43 WDR 2012, supra note 1. Expanding Women’s Voice, Agency, and Empowerment 225 tina, as a result of the availability of part-time employment contracts, partici- pation by married women with children in formal employment increased 9 percent and self-employment was reduced by 7 percent as compared to that by married women without children.44 In 41 countries, employees with chil- dren who are minors have additional legal rights to flexible or part-time work schedules, whereas in many countries, part-time work is not legally recog- nized at all.45 There has been progress toward equal rights in the workplace, at least on the statutory side. More than 100 countries now have laws on nondiscrimina- tion in hiring, and 128 have laws requiring equal pay for equal work. Laws against sexual harassment in the workplace are lagging, however, with only 75 countries having formal sexual harassment laws in place. This may be a reflection of underlying social norms that permit such behavior, as touched on above and discussed further below. Legal Pluralism and Its Impact on Women’s Agency Many countries have plural legal systems that formally recognize religious or customary laws alongside statutes. Today, 52 countries recognize customary and religious law as valid sources of law under constitutions. This is most common in Sub-Saharan Africa, where 25 countries formally recognize at least one religious or customary law, followed by the Middle East and North Africa, where 11 countries constitutionally recognize alternative sources of law.46 The recognition of legal pluralism is generally welcome—reflecting the right of all communities to their own cultures and for indigenous communities the right to determine their own systems of law and justice.47 Plural legal systems are not inherently good or bad for women’s agency; the value depends on the extent to which such systems (both statutory and customary) are nondiscriminatory.48 In practice, as documented below, plu- ral legal systems can create barriers for women’s rights and access to justice. The plurality may affect both the content of the law—in Indonesia, there are six official religions and the state recognizes different provisions regulating marriage and divorce for each—and the process—in the United Kingdom, the 1996 Arbitration Act allows for private religious arbitration by Jewish and Muslim organizations on some disputes between spouses.49 44 WDR 2012, supra note 1. 45 WBL, supra note 8. 46 WBL, supra note 8. 47 UN General Assembly, United Nations Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples, UN GA Res. 61/295 (2007). 48 Sandra Fredman, Anti-discrimination Laws and Work in the Developing World: A Thematic Over- view (forthcoming). 49 UN Women (2011–2012), supra note 28. The World Bank Legal Review226 Legal pluralism matters for the exercise of women’s agency because the scope of customary or religious laws often pertains to marriage, divorce, assets and land ownership, inheritance, or other “personal” laws. Legal pluralism can give rise to gender discrimination in family laws, gender-based violence, and procedural bias. In at least 28 countries, parallel legal systems are exempt from meeting constitutional standards, such as nondiscrimination or equal protection pro- visions. Among these countries, 20 differentiate between men and women in areas covering access to institutions and 15 differentiate between men’s and women’s legal capacity to own, manage, control, and inherit property.50 Formal and informal customary and religious laws sometimes contra- dict constitutional or statutory gender parity. The constitution of Botswana expressly exempts laws pertaining to divorce, adoption, marriage, and de- volution of property and other personal and customary laws from the con- stitutional equality guarantee. This exemption has permitted continuing dis- crimination against women in customary law and practice, including early marriage, polygamy, and the continued practice of legal guardianship by men of unmarried women.51 In the Philippines, despite the constitutional guaran- tee of equality before the law, the Code of Muslim Personal Laws permits polygamy and the marriage of girls under 18. Forced marriages are also still tolerated under this system.52 In other countries, including Kenya53 and South Africa, the constitution overrides such laws in cases of inconsistency, subordinating them to the over- riding principle of equality. In South Africa, the bill of rights has enabled women to challenge discriminatory elements of customary law on the basis of their unconstitutionality.54 Plural legal systems can create barriers to women accessing justice. Mul- tiple systems can lead to a complex web of overlapping systems, which can in turn generate gaps and exacerbate the challenges women already face in real- izing their legal rights. Multiple legal systems can mean that issues such as do- mestic violence are dealt with by alternative dispute-resolution mechanisms, often with the effect of decriminalizing the offense or allowing scope for the male perpetrator or his family to influence the victim. In Brazil, special crimi- nal courts were set up as a form of alternative dispute resolution mechanisms for minor offenses. In practice, 60 to 80 percent of plaintiffs were women, mainly bringing complaints of physical abuse and threats. Reportedly, 50 WBL, supra note 8. 51 S.15, Constitution of Botswana, as discussed in Fredman, supra note 48. 52 Fredman, supra note 48. 53 There is a limited exception for the Khadis courts, applying Muslim law; see WBL, supra note 8. Apart from that, no other customary or personal-status law is exempt, as made explicit in Article 2(4) and Article 60(1)(f) of the Constitution of Kenya. 54 South Africa Constitution, Section 39(3). Expanding Women’s Voice, Agency, and Empowerment 227 90 percent of domestic violence cases ended at the first stage of conciliation, either because of intimidation by the accused or because the judge pressed for the case to be closed. Recognizing the negative impact of the trivialization of these crimes, Brazil passed a new law on domestic and family violence in 2006, ending the practice.55 Laws in Practice—Barriers to Access and Enforcement The expansion of economic opportunities, the adoption of progressive laws, and the evolution of legal systems are all critical to—indeed, necessary for— translating women’s rights into the true exercise of agency, but they are not sufficient on their own. Lack of access to justice for women in many parts of the world persists. This can be explained in part by the unaffordable costs of justice or the lack of awareness of rights. Women can be more adversely af- fected by lack of access due to lower incomes, lower literacy, less mobility, and more restricted social networks. Lack of mobility and time, as well as social stigma and psychological trauma involved in bringing claims, often impedes women from seeking justice. When combined with rigid social norms, these factors can prevent women from seeking and receiving justice according to the rights they already have. The vast majority of countries formally grant equal access to the court system for men and women. However, in 11 countries (the Islamic Republic of Iran, Kuwait, Malaysia, Oman, Pakistan, Saudi Arabia, Sudan, the Syrian Arab Republic, the United Arab Emirates, the West Bank and Gaza, and the Republic of Yemen), the testimony of a woman carries less evidentiary weight than that of a man in family law cases. In the Democratic Republic of Congo, married women need the permission of their husbands to initiate legal pro- ceedings in court.56 Women face a range of social barriers to accessing the justice system. These can include a lack of knowledge about legal rights, dependence on male rela- tives, and restriction of mobility, as well as the threat of social stigma outlined above. In Uganda, statutory land reform resulted in more ownership rights for women than traditional practices had accorded them, yet many women were unaware of these new rights or were precluded in practice due to the high cost of legal procedures and/or loyalty to customary practices.57 In some communities, social norms dictate that women cannot approach the justice system without the assistance of a male relative. This is the case in Timor-Leste, where 58 percent of Timorese, both men and women, disapproved 55 See UN Women (2011–2012), supra note 28, for discussion. 56 WBL, supra note 8. 57 Debbie Budlender & Eileen Alma, In Focus: Women and Land, Securing Rights for Better Lives (International Development Research Centre 2011). The World Bank Legal Review228 of women speaking on their own behalf in local disputes.58 A lack of voice in household decisionmaking can also impede women from being sufficiently empowered to bring a claim before the justice system. A woman’s limited con- trol over household property and assets can make her less likely to bring a claim of domestic violence, for example, because the case is likely to be taken against a family member upon whom she may be financially reliant. Social stigma in the case of sexual and domestic violence is a significant barrier in both developed and developing countries. In Haiti, fear of social stigmatiza- tion and retribution, as well as distrust in the ability of the judicial system to protect them, causes many female victims of sexual violence to remain silent. It may also prevent victims from seeking medical attention.59 Institutional barriers pose a significant challenge. Courtrooms may be dis- tant and costs may be unaffordable. In Kenya, a formal claim for land in an inheritance case can involve up to 17 different legal steps, which translates into legal fees of as much as US$780. Service providers, including police, law- yers, and court officials, may not be versed in or responsive to women’s needs. Data on sexual violence and robbery demonstrate that underreporting of of- fenses by women results from the interaction of these various factors. Across 57 countries, 10 percent of women say they have experienced sexual assault, but among those victims, only 11 percent reported the assault.60 And where women lack access to or control over financial resources or independent in- come, the financial costs of pursuing legal recourse in the absence of free legal aid can be prohibitive. Police, court staff, and even judges often reflect the discriminatory atti- tudes of wider society, and in some cases they may not be fully aware of the rights pertaining to women. This situation provides an additional barrier to women’s access to justice and results in women facing hostility or push-back from the very people who are supposed to uphold their rights. The first step in overcoming this barrier is better representation of women in the organizations charged with implementing and enforcing the law. Quotas have been used in Ethiopia, where one member on each land committee must be a woman. The benefits of this representation have been twofold—it has helped raise aware- ness about land issues among local women, and it has increased their partici- pation in the land registration process.61 The CEDAW committee expressed concern about bias in judicial deci- sionmaking that stemmed from a complaint lodged by a rape survivor in the Philippines, which alleged that societal misconceptions about rape—such as the idea that rape victims are timid or easily cowed and that when a woman 58 Asia Foundation (2008), as reported in UN Women (2011–2012), supra note 28. 59 Lisa Davis & Blaine Bookey, Respecting the Right to Health of Haitian Women and Girls, 13(1) Health & Hum. Rights (2011). 60 Lovett & Kelly (2009), as reported in UN Women (2011–2012), supra note 28. 61 N. Kumar & A. Quisumbing, Policy Reform towards Gender Equality in Ethiopia: Little by Little the Egg Begins to Walk (Institute for Food Policy Research 2010). Expanding Women’s Voice, Agency, and Empowerment 229 knows her attacker, consent is implied—were relied on by the judge in ac- quitting her alleged rapist.62 A 2004 report of the World Bank Workshop on the Development Implications of Gender-Based Violence demonstrates that women’s access to justice in the context of gender-based violence needs to be improved. In particular, the report notes that many judges and other legal pro- fessionals lack the necessary knowledge about gender-based violence to apply international conventions on women’s rights, and that empowering ministries for women’s affairs is essential because they can play a central role in creat- ing the political space needed for this issue to be included more frequently in policy dialogue.63 There are some promising cases of reform in this area. Women in Indone- sia identified high court fees as an obstacle to obtaining divorce certificates, which are required to access social assistance programs such as free health care, cash transfers, and subsidized rice. In response, the World Bank, in col- laboration with PEKKA—an Indonesian NGO that works with more than 12,000 female heads of household across 330 villages to raise awareness of women’s legal rights and to improve women’s access to justice through for- mal legal processes—encouraged the Supreme Court to waive court fees for poor women and to hold circuit courts in rural areas. This quadrupled the number of people in remote areas who have been able to access the courts for family law matters. The Bank also worked with PEKKA to provide training for village paralegals on issues related to family law and domestic violence. To promote greater understanding among government officials, a World Bank project in Kosovo is working with Municipal Cadastre Offices (land management offices) to implement more accurate procedures for registering land transactions, in part by ensuring that their practices are fully following the law, including the Gender Equity and Family Law, in all areas related to inheritance, purchasing, or the sale of property and mortgages. The goal is to help ensure that women receive their inheritance rights, that married wom- en’s rights are properly registered, and that married women actually agree to the transactions made by their husbands.64 World Bank Projects Have Unintended, yet Positive, Effects on Increasing Women’s Agency through Access to Justice A project in Jordan aimed to enhance community-driven legal aid services to the poor. The project was housed within offices of an NGO providing social welfare services, which allowed women to seek advice without attracting at- tention or hostility from their community. During a two-year period between 62 UN Women (2011–2012), supra note 28. 63 World Bank, Report on the Outcomes of the Workshop: The Development Implications of Gender- Based Violence (Gender and Development Group, PREM 2004). 64 World Bank, Mainstreaming Methods to Improve Property Rights in the Kosovo Real Estate Cadas- tre and Registration Project (World Bank 2012). The World Bank Legal Review230 2009 and 2011, it provided free or reduced-cost legal counseling for 700 peo- ple; more than 70 percent of its clients were women. Inspired by the example, the Jordan Center for Legal Aid, with the Jordan Bar Association, created the first pro bono lawyers’ association. The association provides a system of “one- stop shops” for legal aid and counseling and improves access to and quality of service. The Ministry of Social Welfare agreed to refer poor women in need of assistance to the Justice Center for Legal Aid. In Vietnam, the World Bank has provided ongoing support to the govern- ment to foster effective implementation of the 2007 Law on Gender Equal- ity and the National Strategy on Gender Equality. The National Strategy on Gender Equality set out 5 objectives and 20 quantitative targets to eliminate discrimination and ensure women’s equal rights in the fields of labor employ- ment, education, and health care; to improve the quality of women’s partici- pation in economic, political, and social fields; and to enhance the capacity of national machinery for the advancement of women. To further these goals, the World Bank supported awareness raising and capacity building within relevant ministries, and worked with these ministries to build systems of ac- countability, including through a series of development policy loans. Social and Cultural Norms Interact with Laws The persistence of patriarchal attitudes and deep-rooted gender stereotypes in relation to women’s roles and responsibilities perpetuates gender inequality and limits the extent to which formally recognized women’s rights can be real- ized in practice. As eloquently noted by Devaki Jain in her review of the United Nations’ 60-year quest for equality and justice, “Many cultural traditions have embargoes on many dimensions of women’s concerns and freedom. It is here that culture clashes with women’s access to the universality of human rights; often traditions and religious practices hurt and discriminate.”65 In this sense, disequalizing social norms and values can prevent laws from removing con- straints to agency. A stark example of the impact norms can have on women’s empower- ment, voice, and agency is the restriction on women’s mobility. Legal restric- tions on mobility are present in certain countries: 4 of the 141 countries in- cluded in Women, Business, and the Law legally restrict married women from leaving the home in the same way as a man; 16 countries restrict married women from getting a job in the same way as a man; and in 22 countries, married women cannot apply for a passport in the same way as a man. Social norms in many more countries dictate what is acceptable behavior for women. In all 19 countries included in the WDR 2012 qualitative study on gender and economic choice, for example, social norms were the most frequently cited constraint on women’s physical mobility. In Malawi, social norms deterred 65 Devaki Jain, Women, Development and the UN: A Sixty-Year Quest for Equality and Justice, United Nations Intellectual History Project (Indiana U. Press 2005). Expanding Women’s Voice, Agency, and Empowerment 231 pregnant women from using a bicycle ambulance that was set up to improve emergency obstetric care.66 Social norms can interact with formal laws to dictate the extent to which women’s higher personal incomes translate into greater voice and bargaining power within the household. About 20 percent of the participants in the WDR 2012 qualitative study said that husbands have complete control over their wives’ income. Participants also reported that when women do not retain con- trol over their earnings, the potential empowering role of those earnings is limited. High rates of domestic or gender-based violence can be traced to prevail- ing norms. Several countries with serious problems of violence against women have passed legislation relating to domestic and other violence—Bangladesh, Brazil, Nepal, the Philippines, and Zambia—yet patterns of violence contin- ue. A World Health Organization multicountry study revealed that 13 to 61 percent of women experience physical violence in their lifetime,67 while more than 60 percent of women in Bangladesh experience some form of domes- tic abuse during their lifetime.68 Thus, although legislation protecting against such behavior is critical, so is the effective implementation of laws and revised cultural perspectives about the acceptability of violence. Because prevailing social norms in a number of areas can limit the effect of laws to the detriment of gender equality, concerted efforts on this front are needed. Gender norms can be persistent and resilient to change. This is par- ticularly true when an increase in women’s empowerment and agency threat- ens the balance of power within households and communities. The good news is that change is possible. In India, increased female leadership influenced adolescent girls’ career aspirations and educational attainment. Following a 1993 law that reserved female leadership positions for women in randomly selected village councils, the gender gap in career aspirations closed by 25 per- cent in villages that were assigned a female leader for two election cycles, and the gender gap in adolescent educational attainment was erased completely, with girls spending less time on household chores.69 66 K. Lungu et al., Are Bicycle Ambulances and Community Transport Plans Effective in Strengthen- ing Obstetric Referral Systems in Southern Mali? 13(2) Malawi Med. J. 16–18 (2001). 67 World Health Organization, WHO Multi-country Study on Women’s Health and Domestic Vio- lence against Women (WHO 2005). 68 L. M. Bates et al., Socioeconomic Factors and Processes Associated with Domestic Violence in Rural Bangladesh, 30(4) Intl. Family Planning Perspectives 190–99 (2004). 69 Lori Beaman et al., Female Leadership Raises Aspirations and Educational Attainment for Girls: A Policy Experiment in India (2012), available at http://www.sciencexpress.org/12 January 2012/Page 1/10.1126/science.1212382. http://www.sciencexpress.org/ The World Bank Legal Review232 Conclusions This chapter has considered how laws can enhance or limit women’s voice and agency. There are several highlights. First, discrimination persists in many formal statutory legal systems, especially for married women. Second, many countries have plural systems of law related to marriage, divorce, succession, or other “personal” issues that limit rights that may exist. Third, the enforce- ment of rights and the ability for women to seek redress are critical if rights are to encourage the exercise of voice and agency. Finally, and also related to enforceability, social and cultural norms interact with laws to limit or enhance their effectiveness. Although there has been much progress on the front of enhancing wom- en’s voice, agency, and empowerment, the challenges that remain are signifi- cant. The dearth of gender-disaggregated data is also a limiting factor, imped- ing the policy and advocacy work necessary to reform laws. The priorities now are twofold: legal reform is critical. But legal reform alone is insufficient. It must be combined with changes in accessibility and enforceability of laws and changes in social norms around gender roles and women’s abilities. Such norms can limit the effect of laws, services, or incomes to the detriment of women’s voice, agency, and empowerment. By employing innovative approaches, legal structures have the potential to significantly in- crease women’s agency. The World Bank has a strong track record in working in partnership to promote women’s voice, agency, and empowerment through financing, innovation and learning, and investing in data and knowledge to help better understand and address the underlying inequalities. 233 “We Want What the Ok Tedi Women Have!” Guidance from Papua New Guinea on Women’s Engagement in Mining Deals Nicholas MeNzies aNd GeorGia harley Despite global gender equality gains in education, life expectancy, and labor force participation, two areas of persistent inequality remain: asset gaps and women’s agency.1 In many developing countries, including Papua New Guinea (PNG), natural resources are citizens’ key asset. Women’s agency over these assets—their ability to make choices and transform those choices into actions and outcomes (or more simply, the ability to define goals and act on them)—is commonly weak. This is especially so when the resources are accessed for capital-intensive development. Empowering women to exercise agency and control over natural resources and the revenues that flow from them is thus an important contemporary focus for engagements related to gender equality and economic development. The mining regulatory regime in PNG provides a relatively strong posi- tion for communities. Agreements between the state, companies, and impact- ed communities commonly include significant community benefits, such as a share of royalties and an equity stake in the mine. However, significant gender inequality, both locally and at the national level, means that women’s voices are rarely represented in agreement making.2 Women end up with control of The authors would like to thank Belden Dasa, Musje Werror, Nigel Parker, Ian Middleton, Jamila Abassi, Almah Tararia, Patricia Kassman, Nicole Haley, Adriana Eftimie, Waafas Ofosu- Amaah, Lwanzo Amani, Sakuntala Akmeemana, Laura Bailey, and Phillipa Carr, who were closely involved in the design, implementation, and write-up of this work. Even so, errors of fact and interpretation are those of the authors, as are the views expressed in this paper, which should not be attributed to the World Bank, its executive directors, or the countries they represent. 1 World Bank, World Development Report 2012 Gender Equality and Development. Strengthen- ing the role of women in household and community decision making has been shown to have positive development impacts, as women tend to prioritize productive expenditures for their families and communities (including for food, health, and education) over unpro- ductive consumption (such as of alcohol, cigarettes, and gambling). 2 Prior to the 2012 election, when three women were elected at once, only three women had ever been elected in the 37-year history of PNG’s parliament. Moreover, roughly two-thirds of women experience gender-based violence in their lifetimes, and maternal mortality rates are some of the highest in the region. The World Bank Legal Review234 few, if any, benefits, while bearing a disproportionate burden of the social and environmental costs of mining.3 The Ok Tedi mine, located in the northern corner of PNG’s Western Prov- ince, is an exception, albeit qualified, to this general state of affairs. The prov- ince receives a significant share of mining revenues, yet service delivery in the area remains weak. On top of provincial government revenues, impacted communities have received benefits totaling more than 2 billion PNG kina (US$980 million) over the past decade.4 Revised compensation agreements at the Ok Tedi mine, called Community Mine Continuation Agreements (CMCAs), concluded in 2007 are an encouraging innovation.5 Women had a seat at the negotiating table and secured an agreement giving them 10 percent of all benefits, 50 percent of all scholarships, cash payments into family bank accounts (to which women are cosignatories), and mandated seats on the gov- erning bodies implementing the agreement (including future reviews of the agreement). Women’s entitlements are elevated to legally enforceable rights at the heart of the mining company’s license to operate. Such an arrangement is unprecedented anywhere in the world. At the 2010 Women in Mining conference in the town of Madang,6 women from mining communities across PNG exclaimed, “We want what the Ok Tedi women have!” This chapter is based on research in the North Fly (one of three areas impacted by the 2007 agreement).7 It explores the process of negotiation and progress in implementation of the agreement, examining how the agree- ment came about, assessing whether its promise is being realized in practice, 3 See, for example, M. Macintyre, Modernity, Gender and Mining: Experiences from Papua New Guinea, in Gendering the Field: Towards Sustainable Livelihoods for Mining Communities (ANU E- Press 2011). See also M. Macintyre, Petztorme Women: Responding to Change in Lihir, Papua New Guinea, Women’s Groups and Everyday Modernity in Melanesia, 74 (1–2) Oceania (Special Issue) 120–33 (2003). The experience of some indigenous communities in Australia and Canada provides examples of women playing key roles. See C. O’Faircheallaigh, Women’s Absence, Women’s Power: Indigenous Women and Negotiations with Mining Companies in Australia and Canada, Ethnic and Racial Studies 1–19 (2012). 4 Mine operator, Ok Tedi Mining Limited (OTML) data. 5 The five main benefit streams under the CMCAs are cash (the mine operator disburses cash into a mix of family and some clan bank accounts with an annual payment per person); vil- lage projects (each village submits applications for small-scale projects and goods, such as water tanks, outboard motors, and animal husbandry); investments (the foundation invests funds in projects to earn an ongoing return, such as passenger and cargo vessels on the Fly River, housing in Kiunga, and passenger planes); school scholarships (primary, secondary, and tertiary); and the Women and Children’s Fund (10 percent of all benefits are set aside for women, whose use is to be decided upon by women’s groups). 6 The third in a series of meetings focused on communities and women in mine-affected areas, sponsored by GoPNG and the World Bank as part of the ongoing sectoral program of techni- cal assistance financed by the Bank in PNG. 7 Villages visited for this research were mine villages (Finalbin); river villages (Atkamba, Moian, and Yogi); and road villages (Ningerum, where people came from other road villages to participate in focus group discussions). All villages were in North Fly District (except for Moian, which is in Middle Fly). Impacts and conditions in Middle and South Fly districts are known to be different and are not covered in this study. “We Want What the Ok Tedi Women Have!” 235 and providing guidance for mining and gender practitioners hoping to use mining agreements to improve development outcomes for women, both in PNG and farther afield. Underpinning the approach to assessing the implementation of the agree- ment are two widely held tenets of contemporary development practice: • Community-driven development (CDD) has played an increasingly im- portant role in fragile institutional contexts. Rather than treating poor and marginalized people as the target of poverty-reduction efforts, CDD gives control over planning decisions and investment of resources to community groups and local governments—it operates on principles of empowerment, community ownership, participatory governance, greater downward accountability, and enhanced local capacity.8 Complexity of- ten undermines accountability and transparency, and thus key principles, such as clear and simple rules of the game and access to information, are crucial to the premise of CDD. • A political economy approach to delivering development programs is one that is designed to mitigate some key risks (such as elite capture and leakage) through a better understanding of existing power structures and patronage systems and by working actively to overcome constraints. Implementation is an ongoing process of measuring progress against ar- ticulated development objectives and adjusting delivery of the program accordingly. Background of the Ok Tedi Mining Negotiations The history, ownership structure, and importance of Ok Tedi to PNG’s economy have been critical in shaping the negotiation process and outcomes. The mine and affected communities have been engaged in long-running disputes that primarily concern significant environmental damage from the disposal of tailings and mine waste into the Ok Tedi and Fly river systems.9 The disputes occur in the historical context of tension over the impacts of the Panguna mine on Bougainville, which led to conflict and the creation of an au- tonomous region with a pathway to independence from PNG. Issues of con- cern regarding the Ok Tedi mine include loss of fish stocks and water sources, increased flooding leading to the destruction of forests and food gardens, and increased mosquito-borne diseases. Residents along the road between the 8 Experience has shown that given clear rules of the game, access to information, and appro- priate capacity and financial support, poor men and women can effectively organize in order to address local problems by working in partnership with other state and nonstate develop- ment actors. 9 Ok Tedi website, http://www.oktedi.com/community-and-environment/the-environment /impacts-of-mining. The original project design included a tailings dam, but the dam’s foun- dations were washed away in a landslide early in construction in 1984 and were not rebuilt. The national government and OTML agreed to allow the tailings to discharge directly into the river. http://www.oktedi.com/community-and-environment/the-environment/impacts-of-mining http://www.oktedi.com/community-and-environment/the-environment/impacts-of-mining The World Bank Legal Review236 Figure 1. Map of Western Province, PNG Source: World Bank. “We Want What the Ok Tedi Women Have!” 237 mine and the river port in Kiunga also complain about dust from passing con- voys. According to an independent environment expert, the riverine impacts are likely to be felt for “several hundred years” and are borne more heavily by women, who are traditionally responsible for crop production, than by men.10 In 1994, affected communities mounted a class action lawsuit against the mine’s then major shareholder, BHP Pty Ltd, in the Supreme Court of Victoria, Australia, (where BHP is registered). The case was settled with a US$500 mil- lion payout and a commitment to contain tailings and mine waste disposal.11 The case drew international interest at the time for its use of tort law to secure the accountability of a multinational company for environmental damages.12 In 2000, due to community complaints about the mine’s continued use of riverine tailings disposal and the mine’s concern about ongoing environ- mental liability, BHP queried whether the mine should close.13 The mine is the single largest contributor to the PNG economy,14 and thus the state had, and still has, a strong interest in its continued operation. To allow operations to continue, the mine’s majority shareholding was divested to a development trust, the PNG Sustainable Development Program Limited (PNGSDP), beneficially owned by the people of PNG and registered in Singapore to ensure relative independence from day-to-day politics.15 The 10 Alan Tingay, Letter of Endorsement from the Independent Scientist Appointed to the CMCA 2006/7 Review Process (Apr. 16, 2007) (Attachment B to CMCAs). 11 G. Banks & C. Ballard, The Ok Tedi Settlement: Issues, Outcomes, and Implications (Asia Pacific Press 1997). 12 Since the Ok Tedi case, class actions have become increasingly prevalent, including actions taken against Freeport-McMoRan’s Grasberg mine in West Papua, Indonesia; Exxon-Mobil’s natural gas installation in Aceh, Indonesia; Unocal’s oil pipeline in Burma; Shell’s petroleum operations in the Nigerian delta; Rio Tinto’s copper mine on Bougainville; Texaco’s petro- leum operations in the Ecuadorian Amazon; and Thor Chemical’s use of mercury-based chemicals in South Africa. See Banks & Ballard, supra note 11. See also Peter Newell, Access to Environmental Justice? Litigation against TNCs in the South 32(1) R. Crook and P. Houtzager, Making Law Matter: Rules, Rights and Security in the Lives of the Poor, IDS Bulletin 83–93 (2001); Halina Ward, Securing Transnational Corporate Accountability through National Courts: Implica- tions and Policy Options, 24 Hastings Int. & Comp. L. Rev. 451–74 (2001). 13 BHP reported that, even if mining stopped immediately, downstream environmental im- pacts would continue to increase and would likely persist for at least 50 years. Parame- trix, Inc. and URS Greiner Woodward Clyde, Draft Executive Summary: Assessment of Human Health and Ecological Risks for Proposed Mine Waste Mitigation Options at the Ok Tedi Mine, Papua New Guinea; Screening Level Risk Assessment, prepared for Ok Tedi Mining, Ltd., 1–13 (Aug. 13, 1999), available at http://www.oktedi.com. 14 In 2010, export earnings represented 18 percent of the country’s GDP, and taxes and divi- dends to the national government represented 18 percent of tax revenue and 17 percent of government domestic revenue. 15 The PNGSDP comprises a long-term fund and a development fund. The long-term fund in- vests two-thirds of the net income received from OTML in low-risk investments for the future benefit of the people of PNG after the mine’s closure. It has a balance of more than US$1.2 billion. The development fund invests one-third of net income received from OTML in sus- tainable development projects. Two-thirds of those projects are national and one-third are focused in Western Province. For a full description of BHP’s exit strategy and the PNGSDP, see http://www-wds.worldbank.org/external/default/WDSContentServer/WDSP/IB/20 http://www.oktedi.com http://www-wds.worldbank.org/external/default/WDSContentServer/WDSP/IB/2011/06/14/000333037_20110614052552/Rendered/PDF/624980NWP0P1160ns00trusts0and0funds.pdf The World Bank Legal Review238 PNGSDP invests significant amounts in Western Province, including in com- munities affected by the Ok Tedi mine, which, with other mine-related and government sources, creates a complex web of real and potential benefits for communities.16 The mine was required under law to enter into legally enforce- able consent agreements with affected landowners and users. These became known as Community Mine Continuation Agreements (CMCAs). In 2001, the first CMCAs were negotiated. In accordance with a five-year review period, a revised set of CMCAs was negotiated in 2006 and 2007. The revised set of CMCAs now covers more than 90,000 people in 156 villages stretching from the villages in the Highlands around the mine site near Tabubil, along the Ok Tedi and Fly Rivers, to the mouth of the Fly (see figure 1).17 Negotiation of the Agreement Negotiations between mining companies, the state, and landowners are in- variably subject to extreme asymmetries of information and power. These characteristics reduce the likelihood of equitable agreements and limit the po- tential of mining investment to contribute to development outcomes. Over time, entrenched asymmetries can build tension between the parties and un- dermine the durability of mining investment. The CMCA review process at the Ok Tedi mine addressed these challenges to some extent. For the CMCAs, the experience with Bougainville’s Panguna mine; the long history of dispute, litigation, and engagement around Ok Tedi; the mine’s beneficial ownership; and the advanced stage of the mine’s life were key factors resulting in a more positive consultation process being established. For the 2006–07 review, with over 20 years of experience in the area and pro- duction ongoing during negotiations, the mine operator suffered fewer of the time pressures that mining companies often face when negotiating agreements prior to the commencement of operations. Mine management also responded to the international pressure (from NGOs and multilateral organizations) that the environmental damage and litigation had brought, with a desire to leave an improved legacy. Although not without its challenges, the 2006–07 CMCA review process was in many ways a model one, and the quality of the process was impor- tant to women’s ability to secure the deal they did. The broadly consultative process, significant time taken, and independent facilitation and advice all helped to ameliorate asymmetries and build trust. The review process lasted 11/06/14/000333037_20110614052552/Rendered/PDF/624980NWP0P1160ns00trusts0 and0funds.pdf. 16 In addition to five main sources under the CMCAs, other sources of local projects include the Alice River Trust (set up after the class action suit), mine charitable projects, mine- implemented tax-credit projects, member-of-parliament-controlled constituency develop- ment fund projects, and local government projects. 17 The number of villages has increased over time because some communities that were origi- nally opposed to the agreements have since joined. http://www-wds.worldbank.org/external/default/WDSContentServer/WDSP/IB/2011/06/14/000333037_20110614052552/Rendered/PDF/624980NWP0P1160ns00trusts0and0funds.pdf http://www-wds.worldbank.org/external/default/WDSContentServer/WDSP/IB/2011/06/14/000333037_20110614052552/Rendered/PDF/624980NWP0P1160ns00trusts0and0funds.pdf “We Want What the Ok Tedi Women Have!” 239 18 months and cost K7 million (US$3.4 million), paid for by the mine. See the box below for a summary of the negotiating process. CMCA Negotiations: An Innovation Independent international (the Keystone Center) and local (the Tanorama Network) facilitators were selected jointly by the mine and CMCA community leaders to design, support, and guide the process. Independent legal, environmental, and accounting advice was engaged for communities at no cost to them. Prominent former chief justice of the PNG Supreme Court, Sir Arnold Amet, was ap- pointed as the independent legal observer; he became an adviser to the affected communities. The top-level negotiations were held in Tabubil, the township at the base of the mine. Regional-level meet- ings were held in each of three impacted subregions, and village meetings in almost all the impacted villages. Delegates to regional meetings were directly elected by their village constituencies, and the representatives at the top-level negotiating table in Tabubil were elected from the regional meetings. Women’s Engagement in the Negotiations The quality of the overall process provided a positive environment for women to exercise agency. Yet initially, women were not included at all. In the nego- tiation’s early stages, all community representatives were men. In deference to their understanding of local custom, the independent facilitators did not challenge this situation. As one facilitator noted, “we had to be very careful not to be perceived as undermining local authority or customs.” Instead, fa- cilitators asked the male representatives to ensure that they represented the views of their entire group, including women and children. The on-site nature of the discussions meant that, at least for the regional meetings, some women were able to sit outside the negotiations and listen, even though they were not seated at the negotiating table. As negotiations continued, it became apparent that women’s views were not being represented. The mining company’s management understood that the CMCAs would be more likely to achieve development outcomes if women were involved. One senior company representative reflected that “there would be a payout at the end, and there was some concern that the men may drink that away, or buy jeeps, cigarettes etc.” A delegate noted that “the women were so involved in health and education, they would end up being respon- sible for implementing social projects in the region.” Improved development outcomes could foster community support in favor of the mine and reduce the chances of mining-related complaints. And so it was recognized that women’s voices should be heard in the negotiations. The combined support of the com- pany and independent facilitators was critical in convincing the male benefi- The World Bank Legal Review240 ciaries and the state that women should have a seat at the main negotiating table. With negotiations at midpoint, a women’s delegation was established. As one facilitator noted, “the women were so happy that they had a seat at the table—they felt they had won something already.” Women’s involvement was structured around a single delegate at the cen- tral negotiating table and a separate women’s caucus that gathered outside of the main meeting to formulate negotiating positions. There were also consulta- tions with women in impacted villages. The facilitators worked closely with the mine’s gender desk, which had received prior support from a national-level Women in Mining project18 and had assessed women’s development needs. Ume Wainetti was identified as the women’s delegate. Mrs. Wainetti is from the impacted region yet also has a national profile as former chair of the National Council of Women and current convener of the national Family and Sexual Violence Action Committee. In negotiations, Wainetti used cul- tural cues and tactics, describing herself to other delegates as a “sister and aunty.” Coming from the impacted area, Wainetti could both be more asser- tive and employ a range of emotions with the male village representatives more freely than an outsider. Wainetti ensured that she sat next to the mining company managing director at key moments. Presentations of health statis- tics for women and children, combined with emotive personal stories, helped to influence the men at the table. One facilitator observed that Wainetti was “one of the best negotiators at the table.” Her competence in this regard likely stemmed from a combination of tertiary education (when most of the other delegates had only primary level), a combination of national status and local roots, and substantial leadership and negotiation skills acquired in national and international settings. In support of Wainetti as the women’s delegate, a caucus of about 20 women constituted an important forum for both education and developing an informed negotiating position that Wainetti would take to the main nego- tiating table. The caucus brought together at least two women from each of nine impacted areas, along with the provincial government’s women’s officer and female facilitators. A side workshop held over several days included in- formation sessions from mine staff and independent experts about the overall mining operation, environmental impacts, and the benefit envelope. Wainetti, the facilitators, and the mine outreach team also visited women in mine- affected villages, exchanging views and developing a shared negotiating posi- tion. As one facilitator put it, “they [the women’s caucus] were great because they were great leaders, great negotiators, not just because they were women.” 18 Launched in 2003, the Women in Mining and Petroleum project (funded by the World Bank– managed Japan Social Development Fund) has included the drafting of women in mining action plans for affected communities, three national conferences leading to a cabinet- endorsed five-year national action plan, and capacity building (including in basic literacy, numeracy, and economic development skills) to allow women to manage and benefit from the resources that accrue as a result of extractives industries. “We Want What the Ok Tedi Women Have!” 241 Initially, the women’s key proposal was that a minimum of 5 percent of all funds be specifically set aside (that is, ring-fenced) for the benefit of women and children. Wainetti described how women “wanted a separate pot to make sure that women and kids were not forgotten as usual.” The proposal was not intended to exclude women from the remainder of the benefits, nor was it intended to be a maximum amount that women would receive—rather, it was to be a separate minimum amount prioritized for specific initiatives for women and children. Drawing on personal relationships and networks, the women’s caucus approached influential players out of session to seek their support for the proposal. One such participant was Sir Arnold Amet, a well- respected statesman. He was supportive, and suggested that they raise the figure. The delegation also secured the support of the mine’s senior manage- ment. The figure of 10 percent was ultimately chosen on the basis that the male beneficiaries would be unlikely to accept more and that 10 percent might fly “under the radar” at the negotiating table. In tabling the proposal at the main negotiating session, the women’s del- egate emphasized the complementary roles of women and men in the com- munity and stressed that “we are not asking for much, only 10 percent.” Following a silence, Amet spoke in support of the proposal, followed by the mining company representative. One facilitator described how “the back- ing of prestigious people was critical to the proposal being supported in the room.” No questions or concerns were raised, and the proposal was adopted unanimously. The women secured additional provisions on an ad hoc basis throughout the negotiation, including • Cash compensation payments deposited into family bank accounts, to which women were encouraged by the mine to be signatories. (Previously, cash was transferred to clan accounts, which were controlled by men and subject to persistent concerns regarding misuse and leakage.) • Fifty percent of all educational scholarships awarded to women and girls, and women would make up half of the membership of the scholarship selection panels. • Women represented in the CMCA’s key local governance bodies, village planning committees.19 Each committee would include two women repre- sentatives out of the five members (or three women representatives out of a maximum of eight members). • Women represented on each of nine regional trusts and on the board of directors of the Ok Tedi Fly River Development Program, the foundation responsible for the agreement’s implementation. 19 Village planning committees engage in a participatory process to identify, plan, and allocate village-level CMCA projects. Committee members are elected every three years in a process supervised by the foundation. The World Bank Legal Review242 To address what was seen by communities as poor implementation up to that point, key tenets of the 2007 agreement were new structures to ensure “a high level of ownership and decision-making power over resources, pro- grams, and projects” by impacted communities. The agreement provides more explicit entitlements for women than any other mining agreement in PNG or, as far as can be discerned, globally. It thus represents an innovation in efforts to empower women to exercise agen- cy over natural resources. However, the deal alone is not necessarily a suc- cess for women. Ring-fencing can be seen as “both a victory for women and a failure.”20 On the one hand, it promises to improve the status of women by of- fering control over a specific allocation of funds. Indeed, effects could be even greater if the women taking up decision-making roles over the ring-fenced funds are able to generate positive spillover effects for women in other areas, such as stronger household decision making, greater participation in political life, and economic empowerment.21 On the other hand, it is hard to argue on its face that control of 10 percent of all benefits for more than two-thirds of the population (once children are included) is fair. Further, if ring-fencing en- trenches norms that women are somehow undeserving of equal participation and equal benefit sharing and excludes women from the remaining 90 percent of benefits, then its effectiveness should be questioned. Some of these issues can be addressed only in the context of implementation. Implementation of the Agreement The novelty of the deal secured for women in the 2007 agreement raised high expectations; experience during implementation has been mixed. Informed Awareness of the Women’s Deal Is Low Research reveals that in many villages, a wide cross-section of women and men had heard about “the women’s 10 percent,” but no beneficiaries were able to explain how much money was available, the process by which projects were selected, or what had been approved to date. Several women complained that they have not received guidance or training on how to access the benefits. “How do we get the money? . . . It is very hard. . . . Since the launching, no- body knows what has happened with the 10 percent. There are no courses on how to apply for the money. Mothers are in a complete blackout.” More posi- tively, male residents did not express any resentment or complaints about the women’s 10 percent other than a critique that the women weren’t using their 20 See B. Sharp, Renegotiating a Papua New Guinea Compensation Agreement: Applying an Informed Consensus Approach, 69 Resource Management in the Asia Pacific, Working Paper No. 69 (2008). 21 See, for example, the impact of reserved seats for women in Indian village councils on at- titudes toward women, investment priorities, and reporting of crimes against women. For a summary of the results and links to the literature, see http://blogs.worldbank.org/impact evaluations/when-women-are-in-charge. http://blogs.worldbank.org/impactevaluations/when-women-are-in-charge http://blogs.worldbank.org/impactevaluations/when-women-are-in-charge “We Want What the Ok Tedi Women Have!” 243 money. This may suggest a “normalization” of women having control over some portion of resources. This lack of understanding of the women’s 10 percent echoes broader con- fusion among communities about the CMCAs in general, mipela no clia (“We don’t understand/we’re not clear”) being the most common refrain when asked about the agreement. Few people (beyond those serving on the village planning committees), could explain the process for CMCA project approval. Even members of the committees did not appear to understand how much money was available for CMCA projects in their village or region. Benefi- ciaries repeatedly expressed a desire for written information—“in black and white”—to dispel misinformation, build awareness, and foster accountability. Representatives of the foundation note the information problem but state that “we can’t get information to 90,000 people”: indeed, the geographical challenges are considerable. The foundation relies on village planning com- mittee chairs to be conduits to the rest of their committee and the village at large. Minutes of meetings, notices, and verbal updates are sent to the chairs for dissemination. One mine representative explained low levels of beneficiary awareness as a function of community “backwardness,” perhaps reflecting an assumption that communities with little exposure to sophisticated finan- cial topics are not able to understand the arrangements. This conclusion—that awareness is inherently and permanently constrained by the exotic novelty of trust funds and financial flows—is not uncommon on the part of community development technocrats and resource company staff. But global experience shows that targeted and skillful discussions at the community level can indeed empower village people to understand and engage effectively quite quickly. The Ring-Fenced Women’s Fund Is Operational, but Impacts Are Not Widely Felt In accordance with the agreement, a separate process was established to make decisions about the women’s ring-fenced benefits, governed by all-women groups elected by women from the beneficiary villages. From 2007 to 2010, K69.8 million (US$34 million) was set aside for the women and children’s fund.22 As of 2012, the major spending decision was to invest in three learn- ing centers. This decision is in line with the intent of the CMCA, which fore- shadowed initial investments in capacity building to allow women to actively engage in development processes—including the informed use of their funds. One learning center is open, and construction of the remaining two centers is yet to commence. Of the money that has been allocated, it is likely that much of it remains unspent. In one region (covering 18 villages), approximately US$20 million of general funds (that is, not the 10 percent women and children’s fund) remained unspent as of September 2011, and figures show up to half 22 This comprises K21.2 million from OTML, K8.6 million from the PNGSDP, and K40 million from the state. The payment from OTML has been made regularly, and PNGSDP funds have been forthcoming for women’s projects. State funding has been more difficult to access. The World Bank Legal Review244 of individual village funds have not been spent. One trustee attributed the underspending to the failure of villagers to submit project proposals. Under- spending seems unlikely to be a consequence of lack of need for community improvements in the face of basic service failures and profound development challenges. A targeted effort to improve, simplify, and streamline the proposal process could yield results. In the villages, however, very few women have heard of the training centers, and neither women nor men report feeling any benefits from the 10 percent deal. Women in the villages often express concern that they are not being faithfully represented in the women’s bodies to decide on use of the 10 percent. Many of the women in these groups are the wives of local ward councilors or village planning committee chairmen, suggesting that elite divides may compound existing gender inequality. In one village, women complained that their representative on the regional women’s group had moved and was no longer resident in the village and did not provide feedback from meetings. Such an impression is reflected more broadly in the function- ing of village planning committees, which appear beset by challenges related to information, coordination, and representation. Communities report that committees do not faithfully represent community interests, “hoarding infor- mation and keeping benefits” for personal or family gain. Committee chairs are frequently reported to no longer reside in the village they represent (hav- ing moved into towns), limiting their ability to identify community needs, convey information, and be held accountable for decisions made. Family Bank Accounts Show Promise The introduction of family bank accounts for disbursing the cash compen- sation component of the agreement appears to be having a positive impact, improving access to resources by both women and youth.23 Unlike with the project component, there is general understanding of the entitlements and the timing of the payments, including among women and youth. In most of the villages visited for this research, male and female beneficiaries reported that women are cosignatories to bank accounts.24 Women reported much greater access to money than under the previous system of clan accounts. They also claim to spend more productively than men, though this has not been inde- pendently verified. Some youth also reported receiving their entitlements in cash from their parents. 23 The compensation amount varies per village but is in the order of K400 (US$200) per person per year, including for children. 24 The exception to this was reported by communities in and around Ningerum. Prior to 2007, most families did not have bank accounts, so the mine and foundation undertook a process to provide bank accounts through two operators, BSP and PNG Microcredit. Bank repre- sentatives traveled to each of the CMCA villages with the requisite paperwork and opened accounts for most families. The mine and foundation encouraged male and female cosigna- tories to the accounts. “We Want What the Ok Tedi Women Have!” 245 Even so, villagers face high transaction costs in accessing the cash com- pensation. As in many parts of PNG, access to banking facilities in the CMCA area is extremely limited. Beneficiaries must travel to one of three bank loca- tions, and travel costs are high. In one example, the cost of return boat-and- bus travel from Atkamba village, on the lower Ok Tedi, to the nearest branch in Kiunga is K120 (US$57). For two parents (as account cosignatories) to ac- cess funds for a family of five, the cost of transport alone would be more than 15 percent of the annual compensation payment. Initial plans to provide bank- ing in boats along the river were shelved due to security concerns of traveling with large amounts of cash. Mobile phone-facilitated payments have yet to reach the CMCA area, although the rollout of mobile towers offers promise in this regard. Family bank accounts appear not to have increased family savings. The foundation, mine, and villagers report that beneficiaries routinely withdraw the annual cash compensation amount in full. Monthly account-keeping fees of K7 (US$3.40) reduce the incentive for families to save money through the banking system. The full withdrawal of funds also poses administrative bur- dens because this action automatically closes the account, which needs to be reopened to receive the following year’s payment. Implementation of the Scholarship Scheme Has Been Partially Successful The implementation of the scholarship program has occurred in accordance with the CMCA. Women currently make up half of the members on the scholar- ship selection panel. However, the selection process requires little discretion— in practice, supply exceeds demand and the money set aside for scholarships each year exceeds the money demanded from all applicants.25 The selection panel simply identifies whether an applicant is from a CMCA village. Schol- arships have been awarded for primary, secondary, and tertiary education in PNG. Full scholarships are awarded to younger students; for older students, the amount is dependent on the student’s scholastic achievement the previous year. This rubric is widely understood by beneficiaries and supported. In practice, fewer than 50 percent of the scholarships are awarded to girls because fewer girls apply. Boys are often preferred for educational opportuni- ties, because a girl’s productive capacity and eventual bride price payment regularly factor into the decision on whether to send her long-distance for formal education.26 Furthermore, few schools have boarding facilities, and parents have expressed a reluctance to send young girls to stay with relatives for long periods in light of security and financial concerns. 25 For example, according to personal communications from the foundation, the Highway (Tutuwe Trust) has allocated from K1 million to K1.5 million per year; Ok Tedi region (Waitri Trust), K500,000; and Nupmo Trust (Ningerum), K200,000 per year. 26 Thanks to a peer reviewer for these insights. The World Bank Legal Review246 More broadly, villagers expressed concern about the lack of economic op- portunities in the region for scholarship recipients (and others) after gradua- tion. Few graduates return to the CMCA area, raising concern for future local economic development. Decision-Making Structures Do Not Reflect the Levels of Women’s Representation Mandated by the Agreement In all the villages visited for this research, the village planning committee included only one woman, rather than the two or three required under the agreement. In most cases, the women’s representative is the wife or a family member of a ward councilor, village planning committee chairman, or other elite male. No committee chairs were women. In the villages visited, few women reported being aware of what the village planning committee does and few women participate in planning for CMCA village projects. Three women have not been appointed to the board of the overarching foundation as required by the agreement. Indeed, there are no voting ben- eficiary representatives—male or female—on the board. The overarching foundation continues to be controlled by the mine, which continues to hold 75 percent of the foundation’s shares. The mine is assisting the impacted communities to set up an association (Ok Tedi Mine Impact Area Association) that could then take a shareholding in the foundation. The mine reports that it has taken longer than planned to build the capacity of the association and its members, and the foundation is working with the executive of the association to achieve this. Yet, two out of four seats on the foundation’s board are re- served for mine company representatives, and the mine’s managing director chairs the board. Furthermore, the CMCA requirement for the mine to transfer equity in the mine to the foundation (for the benefit of the impacted communi- ties) has not occurred. These missed opportunities mean that the foundation has not yet been able to make the transition to a “high level of community ownership,” as called for in the agreement. Lack of Community Ownership Affects Development Outcomes The failure to transfer ownership and control to beneficiaries affects the de- velopment approach adopted by the foundation and ultimately development outcomes. There is a sharp divergence between the views of those implement- ing the agreement (primarily mine and foundation representatives) and the beneficiaries (the villagers) regarding the success of implementation. This is perhaps not surprising, not least because it is difficult for the foundation to visit every village frequently.27 Implementation could benefit from a structured mechanism through which valuable information about community needs, implementation challenges, and grievances—direct from beneficiaries—is fed back to the foundation to facilitate continuous improvement. The reliance on 27 The service standard for 2011 was one visit to each village each year; for 2012, it was an over- night stay. “We Want What the Ok Tedi Women Have!” 247 village planning committee representatives overlooks intracommunity equity issues that often arise in community development. It is hard for mining companies to “do” community driven development. The ethos of mining companies tends to be technocratic, linear, output focused, grounded in the scientific method, and focused on engineering solutions in often-difficult physical environments. Community development, on the other hand, routinely revolves around political dynamics, privileging process as much as outcomes and balancing competing interests and versions of the truth. Although the forms for inclusive community development have been put in place by the agreement, their function currently falls short of community- driven development. This observation is exemplified in Moian village, where the mine arrived to install a water pump. Mine technicians selected a site easily accessible from the village health clinic, but 15–20 meters away from the village’s custom- ary burial grounds. Residents expressed concern that the site was too close to their burial site and suggested an alternative location for the well farther away from the village, with a pipe to bring the water in. The technicians explained to the villagers that this would be more costly and the pipe would be likely to break—thus limiting the villagers’ access to water. They built the pump in the originally proposed location, which was a logical technical choice. The villag- ers do not use the well, which is an equally logical sociocultural choice. The result is an unsatisfying development outcome. The foundation is taking some steps to improve the participation of vil- lagers in project implementation. A skills census has been undertaken in each village to identify resident capacity to assist with projects. However, a focus on local labor is unlikely to result in greater community empowerment in the absence of specific actions that embed community ownership and control. The lack of community ownership is also demonstrated by another situation in Moian village, where neatly erected house poles dot the village. The poles were erected as part of a housing scheme decided on for all villages in the Middle Fly area. Each village received poles (cemented into place) and zinc roofing to connect to water tanks (delivered to the villages). The villages were asked to supply “local content” in the form of bush material for the floors and walls of houses. In addition to the poles and roofing, Moian also received a saw for villagers to cut the bush material. The saw reportedly broke. Land- owners were unwilling to allow a broader group of villagers to cut trees for timber. The sets of poles remain unused, as does most of the zinc. Lopsided tanks dot the village collecting stagnant water. The Broader Impacts of the Deal Have Not Yet Accrued The strong leadership demonstrated by women during the early negotiation phase has not been present in the implementation phase. After a change in women’s leadership, there is no identifiable cadre of women who demonstrate a similar rigor and collective agency in implementation—a challenge given the dispersed nature of the population and poor communication. There are The World Bank Legal Review248 a few positive spillovers for women from the CMCAs, with representatives of the mine and foundation reporting increased attendance and assertiveness of women in community consultations. However, village women report few changes in their own material circumstances, and there are few, if any, signs of greater entrepreneurship, participation in broader political life, or increased bargaining power for women. The anticipated empowerment gains appear not to have accrued. This lack of spillovers is reflected in overall implementation of the agree- ment. Since the original agreements were reached in 2001, more than K1 bil- lion (almost US$500 million at today’s rates) has accrued to CMCA communi- ties (with another K1 billion to the six villages immediately surrounding the mine site).28 Regional coordinators for the foundation report being “treated like the MP” given the amounts of money they oversee.29 Despite the signifi- cant financial flows associated with the mine, there are few visible projects in CMCA villages, basic infrastructure and service delivery are severely limited, rates of poverty are high, and health and education indicators are poor—with women tending to be worse off than men.30 Some reasons for the lack of de- velopment include slow rollout of the foundation and underspending, intra- village divisions, poor village-level decision making, and elite capture. There are, however, very few observable projects funded from other sources, such as local government or from MP-controlled constituency development funds. The topographical and institutional landscape makes this an extremely chal- lenging development context. The largely parallel CMCA governance struc- tures are not linked to government: village planning committees do not coor- dinate with ward development committees, and relations between the mine, the foundation, the PNGSDP, and the provincial government are a topic of continuing concern.31 Looking Ahead: Guidance for Strengthening Women’s Engagement in Mining Agreements The PNG government is considering changes to policy and law to apply the basic tenets of the Ok Tedi Agreements to mining contexts across PNG. From the government’s perspective, the agreement is an innovation worth model- ing. Such policy reform is widely popular among women in other impacted communities, even though the details and shortcomings of the Ok Tedi deal 28 Over the next two years of the mine’s current phase, another K292 million is projected to be received, and further extension of the mine’s life is being considered. 29 As chair of a joint district planning and budget priorities committee for each constituency, MPs have significant control over sizable resources (K6 million in 2008; K4 million in 2009), which provides the potential for strong visibility and influence of MPs at the village level. 30 2007 CMCA Census Report Appendix: Basic Statistical Tables. See also D. Cammack, Chronic Poverty in Papua New Guinea (Chronic Poverty Research Center 2009). 31 There are efforts to address this through a project matrix that captures all the government, foundation, and PNGSDP projects to guide decisions on implementation and funding. “We Want What the Ok Tedi Women Have!” 249 are not well understood. Acknowledging the unique history and context of the mine, the CMCA process provides insights for other PNG resource projects as well as for stakeholders in other resource-rich countries that have “wealth” in the form of resources but suffer regular elite capture of rents, severe gender inequality, collective action problems, and chronic development challenges. With a view to informing future policy and practice in both PNG and else- where and to improving empowerment outcomes for women, the following broad guidance is provided to mining and gender practitioners engaging in these kinds of deals. Guidance for the Negotiation Phase of Mining Agreements • Mine operators can be powerful allies for women vis-à-vis male benefi- ciaries if the business case for women’s inclusion is made.32 In mining areas, stronger roles for women—including as mine employees—may be associ- ated with reduced risk of conflict and increased stability of production. Women should focus on highlighting how their participation increases efficiency in the use of funds and fosters opportunities to generate posi- tive development outcomes while also reducing the risks of complaint, conflict, and disruption of production. • The characteristics of the individual women who participate in negotia- tions can make a real difference to the negotiated outcome. Representatives who combine both local ties with national or international skills and experience can be particularly effective. • Separate caucusing sessions for women, alongside the primary negotiating stream, allow information to be shared, capacity to be built, and negotiat- ing strategy to be developed. • Independent facilitators and advisers (environmental, legal, financial) help overcome asymmetries of information and power, build trust, and ulti- mately construct more equitable and thus durable deals. This is of benefit for all stakeholders, but a transparent, open, and informed process also provides space for capable women. The PNG Mineral Resources Author- ity has an officer (who was involved in the CMCA negotiations) who now advises women in negotiation processes across the country. Although this is a step forward, it cannot be the only mechanism, because the state is also a party to these agreements and thus faces possible conflicts of inter- est. Similar tensions can arise for staff of mine gender desks, thus high- lighting the importance of independent advice in improving negotiated outcomes. • A complex web of benefit streams undermines accountability, making it diffi- cult for beneficiaries to understand their entitlements and know who is responsible for delivering what, let alone demanding performance if it 32 Why Gender Matters: A Resource Guide for Integrating Gender Considerations into Communi- ties Work at Rio Tinto (Rio Tinto 2010), available at http://www.riotinto.com/documents /ReportsPublications/Rio_Tinto_gender_guide.pdf (accessed Feb. 28 2012). http://www.riotinto.com/documents/ReportsPublications/Rio_Tinto_gender_guide.pdf http://www.riotinto.com/documents/ReportsPublications/Rio_Tinto_gender_guide.pdf The World Bank Legal Review250 is not delivered. Complexity provides space for a small elite to exploit community benefits for personal gain; over time, confusion and capture can breed tension and conflict. It is better to deliver resources through a small number of channels that are easy for beneficiaries to understand and transparent in their delivery. This also enhances accountability while minimizing administrative overheads. Guidance for the Implementation of Mining Agreements • Family bank accounts (with women as cosignatories) enhance women’s control of cash compensation payments. Mobile banking could further enhance ac- cessibility of funds in remote areas and strengthen women’s control over funds. Opportunities exist to incentivize savings, for instance, by lowering account-keeping fees, providing returns on investments, and instituting a “bonus” compensation payment or matching grant to accounts that retain an operating balance. In countries like PNG that have an increasingly in- terested banking sector keen to exploit rapidly increasing teledensity and a regulator focused on financial inclusion (the PNG Central Bank), the potential for pilot programs that address the constraints outlined here is significant. • Setting aside scholarships for girls, and having women on scholarship selection panels, may not be enough to overcome cultural and logistical barriers. Further incentives could be built in to enhance gender equality of ed- ucational opportunities, such as a requirement that boys’ scholarships are conditional on a matching number of girls’ scholarships, and supplemen- tary financing for special provisions for girls’ safety and security while attending school away from home. • Public written information reinforces accountability, even in communities with low literacy. Basic information about benefit procedures, amounts, dates, and feedback/grievance channels should be posted in public places, such as community halls, health clinics, schools, and churches, and posters and pamphlets should be distributed widely, summarizing information in lay terms. Mobile phones can also be used to convey information. • The responsiveness and accountability of village representatives to ben- eficiary communities are undermined when representatives do not live in the village—often moving away using the fruits of their newfound status. Consideration should be given to instituting a residency requirement for vil- lage representatives in the village they represent. • Structured feedback and grievance processes increase accountability and ensure that those responsible for project implementation have better information on activity performance and challenges and increase accountability. These procedures should allow beneficiaries to bypass their local representatives, who may be the subject of complaints, and to register mobile numbers to receive periodic texts asking for feedback on local issues. “We Want What the Ok Tedi Women Have!” 251 Conclusion The 2006–07 Ok Tedi negotiation process and the resulting CMCA agreements are innovative in that they secured enhanced rights for women in legally en- forceable mining agreements, even in the context of severe gender inequality. However, legal rights are not sufficient in and of themselves to produce bet- ter development outcomes. Implementation has faced many of the challenges facing other development efforts in PNG: logistical constraints, low adminis- trative capacity, and elite capture. Nevertheless, the prevailing gender asset gaps in the context of the current global extractives boom highlight the need to engage women more proactively in mining agreements and support them in exercising greater agency over those resources. More attention to the princi- ples and experiences of community-driven development, as well as more local political analysis, will likely benefit women’s engagement and outcomes. The particular guidance for enhancing women’s agency—in both the negotiation and the implementation phases—laid out above offers further opportunities to promote women’s equality and, through this, to achieve better develop- ment outcomes. 253 Innovation in Asset Recovery The Swiss Perspective Rita adam Recent international studies have strikingly illustrated the enormous chal- lenges that corruption and similar crimes pose to developing and emerging economies. The World Bank has played a vital role in bringing these prob- lems to light. According to World Bank estimates, developing countries lose between US$20 billion and US$40 billion each year through bribery, misap- propriation of funds, and other corrupt practices. This amount represents 20 percent to 40 percent of the total international development aid received by these countries. Against this backdrop, the importance of efficiently recov- ering assets illicitly acquired by politically exposed persons (PEP) has been increasingly recognized. Over the course of 25 years, Switzerland has become a world leader in the field of recovery of illegal assets held by former heads of state and other PEP. The expansion of expertise in and commitment to asset recovery issues was prompted by the events that followed the overthrow of Philippine dictator Ferdinand Marcos in 1986. The Swiss government reacted to the news within hours by invoking emergency constitutional powers to freeze all assets held by members of the Marcos regime with Swiss financial intermediaries. This immediate and determined action laid the foundation for the subsequent res- titution, via official mutual assistance channels, of more than US$600 million to the new and democratically elected Philippine authorities. In Switzerland today, there is broad political consensus about determined and proactive action on the part of the authorities against illicit assets held by former heads of state and other PEPs. Switzerland has no interest in its finan- cial sector being abused to conceal assets of dubious provenance that should be used to benefit local populations in the form of state-run programs and projects. Questions of reputation and integrity have become key factors in the global competition among financial centers. Switzerland has proven its com- mitment to tackling the underlying problems not only by its active participa- tion in international initiatives but also in the number of cases that have been resolved worldwide. Over the past 25 years, Switzerland has returned to their countries of origin a total of US$1.7 billion in assets acquired unlawfully by PEPs. The World Bank puts the total value of PEP assets returned during the same time period at US$4–5 billion. As the world’s seventh-largest financial center, Switzerland is thus well ahead of other countries in terms of the resti- tution of unlawfully acquired assets. The Swiss authorities have acquired a great deal of experience in the restitution of PEP assets since 1986. One of the main lessons learned is the The World Bank Legal Review254 importance of creativity and innovation in resolving cases successfully. No two asset recovery cases are exactly alike. As the example of the former Ni- gerian head of state Sani Abacha underscores—at US$800 million, the largest sum of money ever returned worldwide—such cases are extremely complex because a large number of banks, countries, and third parties are usually in- volved. Because mutual legal assistance (MLA) procedures often stretch over periods of many years, the interaction between internal and international in- struments in each specific case is of the utmost importance. Following a brief general overview of the Swiss legal framework for asset recovery, this chapter highlights two specific areas that have seen considerable progress and developments in recent years. First, the chapter addresses the creation of new legal provisions tailored specifically to cases in which the state structures in the country of origin are so weak that the restitution of unlaw- fully acquired assets by international MLA channels is impossible. Second, the chapter turns to the Arab Spring and Switzerland’s initial findings on implica- tions for asset recovery. Overview of the Swiss Institutional and Legal Framework to Combat and Return Assets Illicitly Acquired by PEP Switzerland has a comprehensive range of legal instruments and measures in place for turning away assets of criminal origin and for identifying, blocking, and returning them if they nonetheless find their way into the local financial center. Swiss banking secrecy law does not apply to assets of criminal origin and therefore does not impede existing protective and preventive measures in any way.1 The Swiss legal framework rests on five pillars comparable to the provi- sions familiar in many other states. The various elements are outlined below. Prevention of Corruption The first pillar aims to prevent high-ranking foreign officials from illegally en- riching themselves in the first place. Promoting good governance and tackling the root causes of corruption rate highly in Switzerland’s foreign policy. In its development cooperation, Switzerland gives priority to combining measures at the governmental level through institutional reforms and activities involv- ing civil society, such as awareness raising, participative approaches, social audits, and investigative journalism. Due Diligence/Know Your Customer Another pillar is due diligence; Switzerland takes the necessary measures to prevent illicit assets of PEPs from being transferred to Switzerland or laun- 1 For more information, see http://www.eda.admin.ch/eda/en/home/topics/finec/intcr /poexp.html. http://www.eda.admin.ch/eda/en/home/topics/finec/intcr/poexp.html http://www.eda.admin.ch/eda/en/home/topics/finec/intcr/poexp.html Innovation in Asset Recovery 255 dered via the Swiss banking system and thus being brought into legal eco- nomic circulation. Switzerland does not want to function as a safe haven for illicit assets of PEPs. Stringent “know your customer” rules oblige providers of financial services in Switzerland to identify their clients and ascertain the origin of their assets. To comply with these rules, financial intermediaries are required to identify the beneficial owner of assets. When dealing with PEPs, Switzerland’s legislation also stipulates, in conformity with internationally recognized standards, special clarification requirements (enhanced due dili- gence) and requires that business relations with PEPs be considered as involv- ing increased risks. Obligation to Report All financial intermediaries operating in Switzerland are subject to a legal reporting obligation if they become aware, or have reasonable grounds to suspect, that the assets involved in a given business relationship are, or may be, associated with money laundering or terrorism financing, originate from criminal activities, or are connected with a criminal organization. In such cases, financial intermediaries are required to block assets immediately and to notify the Swiss financial intelligence unit, the Money Laundering Reporting Office Switzerland (MROS), without delay. If there is reason to believe that this may be a case of corruption, MROS will alert the criminal prosecution au- thorities, who will conduct a preliminary inquiry into the origin of the assets. If suspicions persist, the competent authorities will initiate criminal proceed- ings for money laundering. International Mutual Legal Assistance Under international standards, the unlawful acquisition of the assets in ques- tion must be proven in judicial proceedings before they can be returned. Inter- national MLA in criminal matters is a central instrument in this examination. The Swiss Federal Act on International Mutual Assistance in Criminal Matters entered into effect on January 1, 1983. It empowers Switzerland to grant legal assistance to countries with which it has not concluded a bilateral agreement. Swiss authorities take care, wherever possible, to apply the provi- sions of the law with the flexibility needed to respond to the specific circum- stances of individual asset recovery cases and to develop creative approaches to resolving them. This approach makes it possible to actively support states that have encountered difficulties in their recovery efforts. This support may be necessary when the state in question is unable to provide all the evidence required or to comply with the formalities necessary in the context of MLA. In such cases, Switzerland can help the state complete the request for interna- tional MLA and might even pay for the translation of such a request so that it can be submitted to the competent Swiss authorities in one of the national languages, as required by the act. In some cases, Switzerland has exception- ally paid lawyers’ fees to enable requesting states to benefit from counseling, thus increasing their chances of recovering embezzled funds. The World Bank Legal Review256 In parallel with the establishment of international MLA where there are sufficient suspicions to justify it, Swiss authorities will instigate criminal in- vestigations into money laundering, organized crime, or similar offenses. The primary channel for any restitution of assets nonetheless remains the interna- tional MLA process, in combination with the associated criminal proceedings in the state of origin, because it is there that the evidence can generally be found that will determine whether the assets were acquired as the result of a criminal act. If the unlawful origin of the assets is evident, Switzerland may under certain conditions return the assets without any legally enforceable forfeiture order from the state concerned, as in the Abacha case, mentioned above. Restitution Switzerland has made it a priority to return unlawfully acquired PEP assets rapidly and in full to their country of origin. As soon as it is established that assets located and frozen in Switzerland originate from a criminal act, authori- ties will determine which form of restitution best takes into account the cir- cumstances of the individual case. Experience over 25 years shows that there is no one-size-fits-all solution. Hence, Switzerland finds an ad hoc solution to ensure that the assets in question will indeed benefit the population of the country of origin. Furthermore, restitution can be a delicate matter if corrup- tion is endemic in the country of origin of the assets. In such cases, finding a way to ensure that the assets in question will not simply be recycled into criminal activities is crucial. Possible approaches in such cases include setting up an independent monitoring mechanism, returning assets via an interna- tional organization that runs projects and programs in the country of origin, or cooperation with NGOs. In the Sharing Act (the Federal Act Pertaining to the Sharing of Confis- cated Assets), Switzerland has a legal foundation on which it can enter into international asset-sharing agreements in cases of organized crime and money laundering. The act provides for the waiver of any share of assets forfeited in Switzerland so that the entire amount is repaid to the country of origin. It is a standing policy of Switzerland to return in their entirety to the state concerned any confiscated illicit assets of PEPs originating from bribery or misappropria- tion of funds, without insisting on asset sharing. Lessons Learned from the Mobutu and Duvalier Cases The Federal Act on the Restitution of Assets of Politically Exposed Persons Obtained by Unlawful Means (Restitution of Illicit Assets Act, or RIAA) is a significant enhancement to Switzerland’s legal arsenal in the field of asset recovery.2 The RIAA, in force since 2011, contains legal provisions tailored 2 See http://www.admin.ch/ch/e/rs/c196_1.html; for more information, see also http:// www.eda.admin.ch/eda/en/home/topics/finec/intcr/poexp/faqria.html. http://www.admin.ch/ch/e/rs/c196_1.html http://www.eda.admin.ch/eda/en/home/topics/finec/intcr/poexp/faqria.html http://www.eda.admin.ch/eda/en/home/topics/finec/intcr/poexp/faqria.html Innovation in Asset Recovery 257 specifically to cases in which the state structures in the country of origin are so weak that the restitution of kleptocrat funds via international MLA channels faces insurmountable barriers. The drafting of the act was prompted basically by Switzerland’s experiences in the cases of Mobutu (the Democratic Republic of the Congo, DRC) and Duvalier (Haiti). In the first case, the Swiss government made use of its emergency powers anchored in the Swiss Federal Constitution to freeze any Mobutu assets locat- ed in Switzerland immediately after the fall of the dictator in 1997.3 In doing so, the Federal Council intended to make it possible for the new government, headed by Laurent Kabila, to submit a request for international MLA within the necessary time frame. Unfortunately, due to the inactivity of the Congo- lese authorities, who failed to supply the information required and to initiate proceedings against Mobutu, the first international MLA procedure had to be stopped in 2003. The Federal Council, confronted with the imminent risk that the frozen assets would become available again to the members of the Mobutu family, felt it was necessary to act. Indeed, in view of Mobutu’s universally acknowledged kleptocracy, the return of this money to the Mobutu family was as unacceptable to Switzerland as it was to the DRC. The Federal Council mandated the Swiss Federal Department of Foreign Affairs to make contact with the Congolese authorities in an effort to find a solution that would al- low restitution of the assets. This collaboration made it possible, after several years of negotiations, to obtain the agreement of the DRC authorities to al- low a Geneva lawyer, paid for by the Swiss Confederation, to begin criminal proceedings in an effort to recover these assets. A lawsuit filed in Switzerland against the Mobutu family on behalf of the DRC alleging the establishment of a criminal organization was not pursued by the Swiss Attorney General’s Office. It decided not to commence investigations because the statute of limi- tations on the alleged acts had already expired. Unfortunately, the Congolese government instructed its lawyer not to contest the decision of the Attorney General’s Office and, in doing so, destroyed all hope that the frozen assets would be returned to the Congolese people. Hence, the procedure was termi- nated, and Switzerland had no other choice but to unfreeze the Mobutu assets after twelve years of relentless efforts to avoid exactly that. Switzerland regards such an outcome as extremely unsatisfactory. It is all the more objectionable that a despot continues to profit from the result of his poor governance even after he has been overthrown—it is precisely his years or decades of dictatorship that weakened state structures to the point that ren- ders the new authorities incapable of successfully conducting MLA proceed- ings with a partner state. The result is that assets that are frozen in foreign fi- nancial centers, such as Switzerland, are ultimately unfrozen and placed back in the hands of the overthrown dictator. 3 See discussion in the section of this chapter entitled “The Arab Spring and Its Implications for Asset Recovery.” The World Bank Legal Review258 It seemed that the Duvalier case would have a similar outcome. Begin- ning in 1986, the Duvalier case went through a period involving MLA. Fol- lowing the difficulties of Haiti to sufficiently substantiate their MLA request, this procedure was terminated in 2002. Again, the Federal Council decided to intervene, given the manifestly illicit nature of the assets in question. After an asset freeze was ordered on the basis of Swiss constitutional powers, ne- gotiations for a settlement were conducted with the government of Haiti, and with the Duvalier family, but without results until 2007. President René Préval indicated his desire to combat the impunity of the Duvalier family and to take possession of the assets with the help of another MLA procedure, which made its way to the Swiss Federal Supreme Court. In early 2010, the court ruled that restitution in accordance with current Swiss law was no longer possible due to the statute of limitations. At the same time, however, the court confirmed that the assets were of illicit origin. While regretting the need to apply the statute of limitations, the court expressed its view that the conditions imposed by the Federal Act on International Mutual Assistance in Criminal Matters “seem too strict for this type of affair.” In making this observation, the court invited Swiss lawmakers to take into consideration the nature of fragile states and to try to increase their chances of benefiting from the restitution of assets. Fortunately the authorities—prompted by experience gained in the Mobutu case—had already embarked on the corresponding legislative work. In an ef- fort to safeguard the Duvalier assets, the government decided to freeze them while awaiting completion of the parliamentary procedure. Work on new draft legislation was driven forward with the highest priority. The Federal Act on the Restitution of Assets of Politically Exposed Persons Obtained by Unlawful Means (Restitution of Illicit Assets Act, RIAA) entered into force in February 2011, just one year after the Supreme Court’s ruling. It makes Switzerland the first nation in the world to have a law enabling the state to overcome the difficulties involved when dealing with another state that is no longer able to meet the requirements of an MLA procedure due to the collapse of all or a substantial part of its judicial apparatus or judicial dysfunction. The RIAA’s innovative approach attracted worldwide attention. Stuart Levey, the former undersecretary for terrorism and financial intelligence at the US Department of the Treasury, described the RIAA as “arguably the world’s toughest law for repatriating the ill-gotten gains of corrupt politicians.”4 The RIAA came into existence as a result of the difficulties encountered by the Swiss authorities in returning assets frozen in Switzerland to such states following the failure of the international MLA process to produce a satisfac- tory result. The aim of the act is to prevent such situations from recurring and to resolve cases of assets that have been frozen on the orders of the Federal Council’s constitutional powers. The RIAA is a subsidiary solution to the Fed- eral Act on International Mutual Assistance in Criminal Matters. In contrast 4 See Stuart Levey, Fighting Corruption after the Arab Spring, Foreign Affairs (online edition, June 16, 2011), http://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/67895/stuart-levey/corruption -and-the-arab-spring. http://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/67895/stuart-levey/corruption-and-the-arab-spring http://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/67895/stuart-levey/corruption-and-the-arab-spring Innovation in Asset Recovery 259 to criminal law, the RIAA makes the distinction between the conduct of PEPs and the unlawful origin of their assets. In this way, it provides for a different approach to the criminal prosecution of the PEP concerned and enables the forfeiture of assets that clearly have been obtained by unlawful means with- out the need for a criminal conviction against the PEP in question. There are three stages to the repatriation of misappropriated assets under the terms of the RIAA: • To prevent an outflow of suspicious assets, the Federal Council may, un- der the conditions outlined in the RIAA, take the first step of ordering that assets be frozen to secure them. • This is followed by the forfeiture of the assets in proceedings under ad- ministrative law. Here, the state appears as plaintiff against the holder of the disputed assets. • Once a forfeiture ruling has attained legal effect, the assets are repatriated to their state of origin in a transparent process. A major innovation of the RIAA is the reversal of the burden of proof in re- spect to the unlawful origin of frozen PEP assets. With the Mobutu and Duva- lier cases in mind, the law provides for a reversal of the burden of proof with regard to the assets’ illicit origin. In other words, forfeiture is justified under the RIAA if the current owner of these assets is unable to prove that the assets are, in all probability, of lawful origin. This concept rests on the assumption that if a notoriously corrupt PEP or associates hold powers of disposal over an amount of assets that are out of proportion to the PEP’s official salary, these assets are, in all probability, unlawful in origin. The RIAA stipulates that the unlawful origin of assets may be presumed if both of the following two conditions are met: • The wealth of the person who has powers of disposal over the assets has been subject to an extraordinary increase during the PEP’s period of of- fice. This provision is intended to cover two cases: one in which PEPs hold powers of disposal, and one in which the person who holds powers of disposal is not the same person who exercised a public office but is one of their associates. An “extraordinary increase” means that there is a significant discrepancy between the income derived from the public office and that generated by the assets concerned that cannot be explained by normal empirical patterns and the country’s overall situation. A similar provision exists in the UN Convention against Corruption, which talks of a significant increase in the assets of a public official that he or she cannot reasonably explain in relation to his or her lawful income. Concrete evi- dence, to be introduced by the Swiss authorities as plaintiff, must prove that the concerned assets have increased extraordinarily over the relevant period. This would be true, for example, of a minister who became a mil- lionaire while in office, despite not previously having had any wealth. Another example is a person associated with a PEP whose construction or service company generated very high profits from public contracts in con- The World Bank Legal Review260 nection with the office in question. The extraordinary increase condition does not, however, apply to assets that have grown as a result of skilled portfolio management on the part of the bank with which the assets are lodged. • There is a notoriously high level of corruption of the state or PEP in ques- tion during the PEP’s period of office. Whether or not the level of cor- ruption is “notoriously high” is determined in a status analysis based on reports from organizations, such as the World Bank or Transparency International, that conduct research work and analyses on corruption is- sues. Typical cases include those of Suharto, Mobutu, and Duvalier. Dur- ing their periods in office, the level of corruption was recognized as high in respect to the persons themselves and the country as a whole. Criminal acts that are not necessarily classified as corruption under Swiss law but that constitute the improper conduct of a public official in other respects (for example, misappropriation of funds, embezzlement, or another un- lawful use of funds) must also be taken into account in this evaluation. The persons concerned can invalidate the presumption of unlawful origin of the assets by presenting a convincing case for their lawful enrichment. In other words, the presumption ceases to apply if it can be demonstrated that, in all probability, the assets were acquired by lawful means, specifically by presenting suitable evidence and explaining suspicious transactions. The Swiss authorities are confident that the innovative approach of the RIAA is a significant enhancement to the legal framework for asset recovery. The first case of application of the RIAA is pending: the planned forfeiture or- der for the Duvalier assets. The corresponding legal action was brought before the competent Federal Administrative Court by the Swiss authorities in April 2011, just two months after the RIAA went into effect. The Arab Spring and Its Implications for Asset Recovery General Remarks The upheavals in the Arab world in 2011 brought the discussion on the freez- ing and recovery of illicit assets attributed to PEPs to the forefront.5 In view of the historic dimension of the events taking place, the Swiss government decided to act very swiftly. Only a few days after the overthrow of presidents Zine el Abidine Ben Ali (Tunisia) and Hosni Mubarak (Egypt), the Federal Council invoked its emergency constitutional powers to make Switzerland the first country in the world to freeze all the assets held with its financial in- termediaries by Ben Ali, Mubarak, and their associates. The Federal Council’s aims were twofold. First, it wished to avoid the movement of any unlawfully acquired assets to other financial centers, thereby evading justice—at least in 5 For more information, see http://www.eda.admin.ch/eda/en/home/topics/finec/intcr /poexp/sperr.html. http://www.eda.admin.ch/eda/en/home/topics/finec/intcr/poexp/sperr.html http://www.eda.admin.ch/eda/en/home/topics/finec/intcr/poexp/sperr.html Innovation in Asset Recovery 261 the short term. Second, its swift action sent a clear signal to the states of origin that Switzerland was willing to accept requests for international MLA so that misappropriated assets could be returned in full as quickly as possible. There were soon signs that this signal had been understood. Just a few weeks after the freeze was imposed, Switzerland received the first requests for MLA from Tunisia and Egypt. A further unilateral freeze on the assets of Muammar Gad- dafi (Libya) and his associates was replaced by a regime of sanctions following the adoption of the corresponding UN sanctions in March 2011. In parallel with the efforts moving through international MLA channels, the Swiss crimi- nal prosecution authorities began their own investigations into associates of Ben Ali and Mubarak on suspicion of money laundering and membership in a criminal organization. The legal foundation for the preventive freezing of assets is given by a specific provision in the federal constitution. Article 184, paragraph 3, reads, “Where safeguarding the interests of the country so require, the Federal Coun- cil may issue ordinances and rulings. Ordinances must be of limited dura- tion.” The Swiss government has made use of this option in several excep- tional cases, starting with the Marcos funds in 1986, to freeze assets. This tactic is a Swiss specialty: no other country practices such “constitutional freezing.” Three months after the freezes with regard to Tunisia and Egypt were ordered, the government conducted an initial review of its action and decided to create a legal basis for the freezing of PEP assets for the purpose of securing them. This resolution represents a clear commitment to maintaining the practice de- veloped over more than 25 years, that is, that Switzerland is willing to freeze assets as a preventive step in extraordinary cases to prevent their flight else- where and to create the best possible conditions for successful international MLA proceedings for the state of origin. The planned legal basis is intended to set out the conditions for a freeze in greater detail and to determine the basic parameters for its implementation. As a next step following the RIAA, it will complete the Swiss legal framework on asset recovery. The successful restitution of unlawfully acquired assets via international MLA channels is a complex undertaking that demands political will, persis- tence, and creativity. Switzerland knows from experience that a close partner- ship between the requesting and the requested states is a key factor. Indeed, as the term “mutual” implies, MLA procedures cannot be successfully achieved by the requesting or the requested state alone. Furthermore, effective imple- mentation of existing norms can sometimes be challenging. MLA proceed- ings are by nature rather static. Hence, in order to successfully address asset recovery, one of the main questions is how best to make dynamic use of the legal framework. This means, for example, that requests for MLA that do not satisfy all the formal requirements are not simply returned without comment or even ignored by the requested state. It is preferable in such situations ac- tively to seek dialogue with the authorities of the requesting state to resolve possible problems such as those that might arise in connection with expert- level meetings. It can also be helpful for the requested state to make an expert in MLA and asset-tracing issues available to the authorities of the requesting The World Bank Legal Review262 state to provide targeted support and address any outstanding questions. To date, Switzerland’s experience with this approach—which was applied to the requests for international MLA from Tunisia and Egypt—has been positive. To take the Tunisian example, the local prosecutorial authorities are professional and competent, but they have handled few corruption cases in Tunisia, for ob- vious reasons. However, thanks to Switzerland’s providing an expert in MLA and asset tracing, by the end of 2011 the Tunisian authorities were able to sub- mit several formally complete requests for MLA to Switzerland. These were passed directly on to the Swiss judicial authorities for a substantive review. Possibilities for Future Action Complex asset recovery proceedings generally involve several jurisdictions. To resolve the issues that this causes, a close partnership between the request- ing and the requested state is required, as is intensive communication be- tween the various states to which requests for international MLA have been addressed when it is suspected that unlawfully acquired assets are being held within their financial sectors. Therefore, since 2001, the Lausanne Seminars have provided a forum in which experts from requesting and requested states, as well as those from international organizations (including the World Bank) are able, at Switzerland’s invitation, to discuss the practical problems of asset recovery. One year after the beginning of the Arab Spring, the purpose of the sixth edition of the seminar, held in January 2012, was to take stock of progress made and to identify challenges with a view to examining possibilities for fu- ture action. Centered on the experiences of requesting and requested states in the wake of the events in North Africa, representatives from Egypt, Libya, and Tunisia voiced their observations and concerns, followed by remarks from re- questing states and third actors, such as the World Bank, the UN Office on Drugs and Crime (UNODC), the European Commission, and the International Centre for Asset Recovery, and an in-depth discussion. While acknowledging the existence and possible added value of domestic criminal investigations con- ducted in requested states, participants agreed that international cooperation through MLA is the prime vehicle for achieving the recovery of such assets. They identified the following key actions for accelerating pending procedures: • Build and deepen effective MLA partnerships based on dialogue and trust between requesting and requested states through the following actions: • Strengthen trust and mutual understanding by developing personal contacts between the competent authorities and persons in charge in requesting and requested states. • Increase dialogue through institutionalized communication channels, for example, regular meetings between experts from both sides, to address issues directly and to ensure consistent follow-up to pending procedures. Innovation in Asset Recovery 263 • Ensure continuity with the competent authorities and persons in charge by avoiding “wandering files.” • Improve the quality of communication; for example, no MLA request remains unanswered. If not all formal requirements are met or other problems exist from the point of view of the requested state, the re- questing state is rapidly informed. • Deepen the partnership between requesting and requested states through the joint determination of possible fields for technical coop- eration, for example, by dispatching MLA experts from the requested state. • Improve coordination mechanisms, at both international and domestic levels, with a view to making relevant information more rapidly and ef- fectively available through the following actions: • Improve coordination at the domestic level by, for example, creating focal points and/or task forces in charge of pending asset recovery cas- es, with clearly attributed responsibilities for each task force member. • Use existing international practitioners’ networks more consistently, for example, in the framework of Interpol, Eurojust, Egmont, and the like, to increase the flow of information. • Create, if needed, new, tailor-made networks and communication platforms or international task forces to share information more ef- fectively. • Explore ways to increase cooperation with financial intelligence units (FIUs) with a view to exploiting more effectively the information and intelligence available in FIU networks. • Collect facts on the ongoing measures of financial centers to sup- port requesting states; for example, develop a matrix of assets frozen, seized, and finally repatriated by (and for) each state in question. • Customize the approach that best fits a specific case, with particular at- tention to creativity and complementarity, through the following actions: • Combine the available instruments, such as MLA proceedings, do- mestic criminal proceedings (for example, for money laundering or for participation in a criminal organization), and civil forfeiture. • Within the existing legal framework, make use of one’s own MLA requests to substantiate partner states’ MLA requests by providing relevant information. • Increase cooperation with third actors such as the World Bank/ StAR, UNODC, and nongovernmental service providers such as the International Centre for Asset Recovery, bearing in mind the impor- tant role they can play in capacity building, as well as with “match- makers” to bridge information gaps. The World Bank Legal Review264 • Explore the possibility of establishing international standard prac- tices in MLA proceedings and asset recovery as a blueprint for action in current and upcoming cases (typical sequencing, main legal chal- lenges to be addressed, and the like). • Actively search for innovative and creative solutions, bearing in mind that in asset recovery, there are no one-size-fits-all solutions. Participants concluded their discussions by expressing the wish for a follow-up to take stock of progress and to keep the momentum developed at the seminar. Conclusions Experience has shown that asset recovery cases raise complex legal issues across several jurisdictions. Resolving these issues demands close and un- wavering partnerships between the states involved, including the states of origin, as well as a considerable degree of tenacity and perseverance. The dy- namic application of the existing legal framework can go a long way toward simplifying efforts via international mutual assistance channels and speeding up restitution. In most cases, innovation and creativity play a decisive role in asset recovery. By its very definition, however, innovation is a process. Each case that is resolved offers new insights that allow the authorities concerned to review their procedures, amend them as necessary, and develop new ap- proaches for the future. Switzerland has a fundamental interest in ensuring that its financial sector is not used as a hiding place for assets of unlawful origin. Since the Marcos case in 1986, Switzerland has gathered a great deal of experience in the field of asset recovery and has refined its national legal framework accordingly. Regular contact with the competent authorities of partner states has been an important part of this development. Switzerland plans to continue this dia- logue through knowledge and experience sharing and will maintain its com- mitment in this area. 265 International Asset Sharing A Multipurpose Tool for Development Karyn Kenny The ability of governments across the globe to work effectively together to identify, seize, and forfeit illicit gains and combat the money laundering and the corruption that stem from these illicit gains is a critical component of in- ternational development. “Taking the profit out of crime” is an important goal within the international asset forfeiture (AF) and anti-money-laundering (AML) community. The need to strengthen AF/AML cooperation on a glob- al level is even more important. As the US Attorney General pointed out in March 2012, “[i]n an era where crime is not limited by physical boundaries, our international partnerships are more critical than ever in the work of bring- ing criminals to justice.”1 One such tool for development that strengthens in- ternational cooperation, builds domestic capacity, and combats transnational economic crime is international asset-sharing programs (IASPs). IASPs are agreements that permit the sharing country to recognize case-related assis- tance received from other countries during a domestically prosecuted forfei- ture and/or money-laundering case. This chapter outlines the components of an IASP and examines IASPs as a mechanism to aid economic and legal development. The chapter first examines the topic of international asset sharing from the perspective of an international organization, specifically, the United Nations (UN). The analysis then turns to a discussion of countries participating in asset-sharing agreements, such as The Bahamas and Canada. Then it explores the US Department of Justice’s (DOJ) IASP program in detail, focusing first on the US legislative framework regarding forfeiture and the DOJ’s management model for forfeited property and funds and then on the manner in which DOJ international sharing agree- ments are structured. The chapter concludes with an overview of the benefits of implementing a transparent and accountable IASP. Interwoven throughout the discussion are the developmental benefits that can be realized by implementing an IASP. Tangible benefits include building international cooperation among justice and financial agencies (for example, Any opinions expressed in the chapter are the author’s own and do not, in any way, reflect the official position or views of the US DOJ. The author would like to thank Hassane Cissé, Thomas Dougherty, Agustin Flah, Jenifer Preston, Matthew Moorhead, Milena Sanchez de Boado, and Linda Samuel for their support. 1 Remarks by the Attorney General of the United States Eric J. Holder, Jr. (Mar. 26, 2012), avail- able at http://www.gsnmagazine.com/node/25953 (accessed Mar. 28, 2012). Mark Rock- well, U. S., Mexico to Split Millions in Seized Assets to Cripple Drug Gangs, Government Security News (Mar. 27, 2012). http://www.gsnmagazine.com/node/25953 The World Bank Legal Review266 financial intelligence units and prosecution and law enforcement agencies), building capacity in domestic AF/AML sectors, and taking money out of the pockets of criminals. UN Support for Asset Sharing Support for international asset sharing can be found in a number of UN con- ventions, including the UN Convention against Illicit Traffic in Narcotic Drugs and Psychotropic Substances of 19882 (commonly referred to as the Vienna Convention), the UN Convention against Transnational Organized Crime3 (commonly referred to as the Palermo Convention), and the International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism.4 Pursuant to UN Resolution 2004/24, the Economic and Social Council, determined to strengthen interna- tional cooperation in the confiscation and disposal of the proceeds of crime covered by the Organized Crime Convention and the United Nations Convention against Illicit Traffic in Narcotic Drugs and Psy- chotropic Substances of 1988, and recognizing that a model bilateral agreement on sharing confiscated proceeds of crime could facili- tate greater international cooperation in that matter, requested the Secretary-General to convene an open-ended intergovernmental ex- pert group to prepare such a draft model bilateral agreement. The group met from 26 to 28 January 2005.5 As a result of these meetings, the UN Office on Drugs and Crime suc- cessfully developed a model agreement on international asset sharing. The UN Crime Commission endorsed this agreement in May 2005, and the UN General Assembly endorsed it in December 2005. The model provides a use- ful framework for countries needing an asset-sharing agreement to facilitate international forfeiture cooperation. 2 Article 5(a) provides that “proceeds or property confiscated by a Party . . . shall be disposed of by that Party according to its domestic law and administrative procedures.” Article 5(b) (ii) encourages the sharing of such confiscated assets with other parties “on a regular or case- by-case basis” in accordance with domestic law or any applicable bilateral or multilateral agreements.” Available at http://www.unodc.org/pdf/convention_1988_en.pdf (accessed Mar. 3, 2012). 3 Article 14 calls for forfeited assets to be disposed of pursuant to domestic law, but “if so requested” the country should “give priority consideration to returning the confiscated pro- ceeds of crime or property to the requesting State Party so that it can give compensation to the victims of the crime or return such proceeds of crime or property to their legitimate own- ers.” See http://www.unodc.org/unodc/en/treaties/CTOC (accessed Mar. 3, 2012). 4 This convention recommends, but does not mandate, sharing. See http://www.un.org/law /cod/finterr.htm (accessed Mar. 3, 2012). 5 See Eleventh United Nations Congress on Crime Prevention and Criminal Justice, Bangkok 6 (Apr. 2005). See also http://www.un.org/events/11thcongress/docs/programme.pdf (accessed Mar. 12, 2012). http://www.unodc.org/pdf/convention_1988_en.pdf http://www.unodc.org/unodc/en/treaties/CTOC http://www.un.org/law/cod/finterr.htm http://www.un.org/events/11thcongress/docs/programme.pdf http://www.un.org/law/cod/finterr.htm International Asset Sharing 267 In addition to the UN conventions, recommendation 38 of the Financial Action Task Force (FATF)6 advocates international asset sharing. Specifically, this recommendation states that [t]here should be authority to take expeditious action in response to requests by foreign countries to identify, freeze, seize and confiscate property laundered, proceeds from money laundering or predicate offences, instrumentalities used in or intended for use in the com- mission of these offences, or property of corresponding value. There should also be arrangements for co-ordinating seizure and confis- cation proceedings, which may include the sharing of confiscated assets.7 In addition to UN support for international asset-sharing agreements, many nations, recognizing the benefits of such agreements, have established their own IASPs. The US Attorney General states, “It is the policy of the Unit- ed States to encourage international asset sharing and to recognize all foreign assistance that facilitates US forfeitures so far as consistent with US law.”8 This chapter examines in detail the components of one such IASP —that of the DOJ.9 Bermuda and Canada—International Asset-Sharing Agreements Bermuda and Canada are two countries that have entered into formal asset- sharing agreements. In March 2009, officials from the Bahamian and Canadian governments signed an asset-sharing agreement that reinforced their shared commitment to confiscate the proceeds of drug trafficking and money laun- dering, among other criminal acts. Prior to the agreement, The Bahamas and Canada had relied primarily on the 1990 Mutual Legal Assistance in Criminal Matters Treaty to exchange information and confiscate illegal assets. A mutual legal assistance treaty facilitates the gathering of evidence and intelligence in the inves- tigation and prosecution of criminal offences. It also enhances the capabilities in the confiscation of the proceeds of crime. Mutual legal assistance treaties are concluded between two countries for the pur- 6 “The Financial Action Task Force (FATF) is an inter-governmental body established in 1989 by the Ministers of its Member jurisdictions. The objectives of the FATF are to set standards and promote effective implementation of legal, regulatory and operational measures for combating money laundering, terrorist financing and other related threats to the integrity of the international financial system. The FATF is therefore a ‘policy-making body’ which works to generate the necessary political will to bring about national legislative and regu- latory reforms in these areas.” See http://www.fatf-gafi.org/pages/aboutus/ (accessed Mar. 10, 2012). 7 See http://www.fatf-gafi.org/media/fatf/documents/40%20Recommendations.pdf, at 13 (accessed Mar. 24, 2012). 8 US Attorneys Manual, Chapter 9-116.000, Equitable Sharing and Federal Adoption, 9-116.400, In- ternational Sharing of Forfeited Assets (2011). 9 The US Department of Treasury maintains its own IASP for cases handled by the agencies that fall within the Treasury’s domain, such as the Internal Revenue Service. http://www.fatf-gafi.org/pages/aboutus/ http://www.fatf-gafi.org/media/fatf/documents/40%20Recommendations.pdf The World Bank Legal Review268 pose of gathering and exchanging information in an effort to enforce criminal laws and confiscate the ill-gotten gains of criminal activity.10 Then, in 2000, “[p]ursuant to the 1988 United Nations Convention against the Illicit Traffic in Narcotic Drugs and Psychotropic Substances, the Government of The Bahamas implemented the Proceeds of Crime Act 2000 (Act), where Sections 52 and 53 provide[d] for the establishment and administration of the Confiscated Assets Fund.”11 Following the passage of the act, the government of the Bahamas expressed a desire to formalize their existing cooperation ef- forts with the government of Canada. In 2001, both countries participated in negotiations that resulted in an agreement to enter into a formal asset-sharing agreement. In 2009, officials representing the governments signed an asset- sharing agreement. With this agreement, Bahamian and Canadian officials were able to strengthen their mutual cooperation efforts in combating interna- tional money-laundering offenders while facilitating bilateral confiscation of illicitly obtained assets. Asset Forfeiture Framework—US Federal Statutes The fundamental building block for any IASP is a strong and comprehensive legal framework. The statutory authority that enables the DOJ to enter into international asset-sharing agreements is found in Statute 18 US Code (USC) Section 981(i), Statute 21 USC Section 882(e)(1)(E), and Statute 31 USC Sec- tion 9703(h)(2).12 Statute 18 USC Section 981(i) sets forth the conditions under 10 See http://www.thebahamasweekly.com/publish/bis-news updates/Bahamas_and_Canada _Sign_Asset_ Sharing_Agreement 5788.shtml (accessed Jul. 19, 2012). 11 Id. 12 Statute 18 USC Section 981—Civil Forfeiture, Section (i), reads, in part: “(1) Whenever prop- erty is civilly or criminally forfeited under this chapter, the Attorney General or the Sec- retary of the Treasury, as the case may be, may transfer the forfeited personal property or the proceeds of the sale of any forfeited personal or real property to any foreign country which participated directly or indirectly in the seizure or forfeiture of the property, if such a transfer (A) has been agreed to by the Secretary of State; (B) is authorized in an international agreement between the United States and the foreign country; and (C) is made to a country which, if applicable, has been certified under Section 481(h) [4] of the Foreign Assistance Act of 1961. A decision by the Attorney General or the Secretary of the Treasury pursuant to this paragraph shall not be subject to review. The foreign country shall, in the event of a transfer of property or proceeds of sale of property under this subsection, bear all expenses incurred by the United States in the seizure, maintenance, inventory, storage, forfeiture, and disposition of the property, and all transfer costs. The payment of all such expenses, and the transfer of assets pursuant to this paragraph, shall be upon such terms and conditions as the Attorney General or the Secretary of the Treasury may, in his discretion, set. (2) The provi- sions of this section shall not be construed as limiting or superseding any other authority of the United States to provide assistance to a foreign country in obtaining property related to a crime committed in the foreign country, including property which is sought as evidence of a crime committed in the foreign country. (3) A certified order or judgment of forfeiture by a court of competent jurisdiction of a foreign country concerning property which is the subject of forfeiture under this section and was determined by such court to be the type of property described in subsection (a)(1)(B) of this section, and any certified recordings or transcripts of testimony taken in a foreign judicial proceeding concerning such order or judgment of forfeiture, shall be admissible in evidence in a proceeding brought pursuant to this section. http://www.thebahamasweekly.com/publish/bis-newsupdates/Bahamas_and_Canada_Sign_Asset_Sharing_Agreement5788.shtml http://www.thebahamasweekly.com/publish/bis-newsupdates/Bahamas_and_Canada_Sign_Asset_Sharing_Agreement5788.shtml International Asset Sharing 269 which the US Attorney General may transfer personal property, or the pro- ceeds from the sale of any personal or real property, that has been civilly or criminally forfeited to a foreign country. The critical component of this statute is that it grants the attorney general discretionary authority regarding sharing agreements. Forfeiture Statutes Forfeiture is the taking, by the government, of property derived from a crime, involved in a crime, or that facilitates a crime, without compensating the owner. Many countries have enacted forfeiture laws in both their civil and their criminal codes. In the US federal system, there are two types of forfei- ture: administrative and judicial. Judicial forfeiture, which requires a pros- ecutor to start a case in court, is further subdivided into criminal and civil forfeiture. Each of these types of forfeiture is briefly discussed below. Administrative Forfeiture Administrative forfeiture is a nonjudicial matter handled by a law enforce- ment agency; the majority of all forfeitures are administrative. In this process, the seizing agency declares the property forfeited without a judicial proceed- ing; this status is reserved for uncontested cases. An administrative forfeiture typically begins with a law enforcement agent making a seizure based on probable cause.13 Each step of the administrative forfeiture process includes procedural and constitutional protections for owners. Following the initial seizure, the law enforcement agency commences the administrative forfeiture process by sending a notice to the party informing it of its right to file a claim for the return of the seized property within a certain period of time. After the period of time has lapsed, and if no claim is filed, the property may be declared forfeited by the federal agency. However, if a claim is filed, the case is referred to a prosecutor for judicial forfeiture, a process in which the party may challenge the forfeiture. Pursuant to US federal law, the seizing or adopting14 law enforcement agency may proceed to administratively forfeit a defined category of items. For example, the following may be forfeited: monetary instruments, such as cash, checks, stocks, and bonds; or conveyances, such as vehicles, vessels, Such certified order or judgment of forfeiture.” 13 “[P]robable cause is a flexible, common-sense standard. It merely requires that the facts available to the officer would ‘warrant a man of reasonable caution in the belief,’ Carroll v. United States, 267 U.S. 132, 162 [45 S.Ct. 280, 288, 69 L.Ed. 543] (1925), that certain items may be contraband or stolen property or useful as evidence of a crime; it does not demand any showing that such a belief be correct or more likely true than false.” United States v. Dunn, 946 F.2d 615, 619 (9th Cir. 1991), cert. denied, 502 U.S. 950 (1991). 14 Under US federal law, a state or local law enforcement agency may request that a federal agency “adopt” a seizure if certain conditions are met, including if the underlying act sup- porting the seizure was a violation of US federal law. The World Bank Legal Review270 and/or aircraft that have been used to commit or facilitate a crime. In regard to other property, such as bank accounts and jewelry, only items valued at US$500,000 or less may be seized. Although most property can be forfeited administratively, an important exception is real property.15 Judicial Forfeiture Judicial forfeiture “is the process by which property is declared forfeited to the United States by a court. This status is required for any property other than monetary instruments and hauling conveyances if the value of the other property exceeds US$500,000; a valid, timely claim has been filed in an admin- istrative forfeiture; or if the property is real estate.”16 Once a property claim enters into a judicial forfeiture procedure, it will proceed as either a criminal or a civil case, depending on the circumstances regarding the seizure. Criminal Forfeiture Because it is in personam, that is, forfeiture against the person, only property that the defendant in a criminal case has an interest in, and that does not be- long to a third party, can be forfeited in a criminal case. In criminal forfeitures, the forfeiture allegation is contained within the criminal indictment.17 If the defendant is convicted, the jury or court hears additional evidence and/or argument on the forfeiture matter. If applicable, the court may also hold a post-trial ancillary hearing to address any third-party interests. Civil Forfeiture Civil forfeiture, also referred to as non-conviction-based forfeiture, is a civil action in-rem, that is, against the property itself, and forfeiture is limited to specific property involved in the crime.18 In this type of forfeiture action, the government must prove that the property, not the person, was derived from, or was used to, commit a crime. In a civil judicial forfeiture case, the case moves through a civil discovery process, with motions practice and trial stages. In terms of burden of proof, the government bears the initial burden of establishing the forfeitability of the property by a preponderance of the 15 US Department of Justice, Criminal Division, Guide to Equitable Sharing for State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies (Apr. 2010). 16 Id. 17 Criminal indictment is defined by the Merriam-Webster Dictionary as a formal written state- ment framed by a prosecuting authority and found by a jury (as a grand jury) charging a person with an offense. 18 In The Recovery of “Criminal” Assets in New Zealand, Ireland and England, 41 Victoria U. of Wel- lington L. Rev. 26 (2010), Liz Campbell observes that “[i]n the same way that a civil action for misappropriation of property seeks to restore the injured party to the position he was in prior to the commission of the tort, it is arguable that civil forfeiture also seeks to return the state of affairs to that before the alleged criminal offence.” International Asset Sharing 271 evidence,19 and the innocent owner defense may be asserted. If forfeitability is proved and the innocent owner defense fails, the court will order judgment for the government. Countries that have incorporated forfeiture laws into their legal frame- work often have a version of the types of forfeiture discussed above. Re- gardless of the approach, the key is a strong legal framework to support the government’s ability to seize and forfeit property in accordance with constitu- tional and due process rights. In the United States, pursuant to Statute 28 USC Section 1355(b)(2), regardless of where the assets are physically located, the government may bring a civil forfeiture action before a federal court. How- ever, a “US court’s jurisdiction over international property is a legal fiction without the cooperation of the foreign country where the property is located. If the foreign country does not agree to enforce a US district court’s civil forfei- ture order, the US government would be unable to seize the property.”20 In addition to a strong statutory-based framework, an effective IASP re- quires the establishment of an agency or office that is tasked with an oversight role regarding the maintenance and accountability of seized and forfeited property and any resulting funds. In the US federal system, these responsibili- ties fall under the DOJ’s Asset Forfeiture Program. The DOJ’s Asset Forfeiture Program The need to efficiently preserve, manage, and (if the forfeiture process is final- ized) dispose of forfeited assets is an important component of any success- ful IASP21 and requires the presence of an agency or a specialized division. Such an agency can work to ensure that seized assets are properly maintained, which guarantees that their value is retained during the pendency of the sei- zure process—an important responsibility—regardless of whether the assets are returned to the original owner or ultimately forfeited to the government. In the United States, this function is carried out for the DOJ by the US Marshals Service.22 The US Marshals Service “has primary responsibility for holding and maintaining real and tangible personal property seized by 19 “A preponderance of evidence is described as just enough evidence to make it more likely than not that the fact the claimant seeks to prove is true . . . the definition serves as a helpful guide to judges and juries in determining whether a claimant has carried his or her burden of proof.” See http://legal-dictionary.thefreedictionary.com. 20 Jorene Soto, Show Me the Money Part II, 13 –14 Oregon Review of Intl. L. 141, 152 (2011), quoting, in part, “See, US v. Meza, 856 F. Supp. 759 (E.D.N.Y/ 1994, aff’d, 63 F.3d 148 (2nd. Cir. 1995).” 21 Agencies participating in the Asset Forfeiture Program must also ensure that data in the property and financial management systems of the program are updated in a timely manner. 22 “The [US] Attorney General is authorized to use the Assets Forfeiture Fund to pay any nec- essary expenses associated with forfeiture operations such as property seizure, detention, management, forfeiture, and disposal. The Fund may also be used to finance certain general investigative expenses. These authorized uses are enumerated in 28 USC. Section 524(c).” http://legal-dictionary.thefreedictionary.com The World Bank Legal Review272 participating agencies for disposition. Seized property can be either returned to the owner or forfeited to the Government. Forfeited property is subsequent- ly sold, placed into official use, destroyed, or transferred to another agency.”23 Moreover, funds that are forfeited to the government must also be managed in a transparent, accountable, and efficient manner. In cases where the seizing agency participates in the DOJ’s IASP, the re- sponsibility for oversight of the funds and program management falls under the power of the DOJ’s Asset Forfeiture Program: The Comprehensive Crime Control Act of 1984 established the De- partment of Justice’s Assets Forfeiture Fund to receive the proceeds of forfeiture and to pay the costs associated with such forfeitures, in- cluding the costs of managing and disposing of property, satisfying valid liens, mortgages, and other innocent owner claims, and costs associated with accomplishing the legal forfeiture of the property.24 The Asset Forfeiture Program operates at the federal level and manages the individual DOJ components that are “charged with lawfully, effectively, and efficiently supporting law enforcement authorities in the application of specified forfeiture statutes.”25 The program was designed to support law en- forcement initiatives across the United States and around the globe to “re- move the tools of crime from criminal organizations, deprive wrongdoers of the proceeds of their crimes, recover property that may be used to compensate victims, and deter crime.”26 The DOJ’s Asset Forfeiture Program comprises two financial funds.27 Funds involving seized and forfeited property are managed in the United States by the Assets Forfeiture Fund (AFF), which works in conjunction with the Seized Asset Deposit Fund (SADF) to create a single financial reporting entity for the DOJ. These funds include the “specified funds, property seized for forfeiture, and the transactions and program activities of the DOJ forfeiture program components and other participating agencies.”28 23 See Assets Forfeiture Fund and Seized Asset Deposit Fund Annual Financial Statements Fiscal Year 2011, available at http://www.justice.gov/oig/reports/2012/a1212.pdf (accessed Mar. 21, 2012). 24 Statute 28 USC Section 524(c). See http://www.justice.gov/jmd/afp/02fundreport/02_2 .html (accessed Feb. 18, 2012). 25 See Assets Forfeiture Fund and Seized Asset Deposit Fund Annual Financial Statements Fiscal Year 2011, available at http://www.justice.gov/oig/reports/2012/a1212.pdf (accessed Mar. 2, 2012). 26 US DOJ, Criminal Division, Guide to Equitable Sharing for State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies (Apr. 2010). 27 See Assets Forfeiture Fund and Seized Asset Deposit Fund Annual Financial Statements Fiscal Year 2011, at 3, available at http://www.justice.gov/oig/reports/2012/a1212.pdf (accessed Apr. 1, 2012). 28 Id. http://www.justice.gov/oig/reports/2012/a1212.pdf http://www.justice.gov/jmd/afp/02fundreport/02_2.html http://www.justice.gov/jmd/afp/02fundreport/02_2.html http://www.justice.gov/oig/reports/2012/a1212.pdf http://www.justice.gov/oig/reports/2012/a1212.pdf International Asset Sharing 273 The Asset Forfeiture Program invests cash balances from both the AFF and the SADF in government securities. “All amounts earned from the investment of AFF and SADF balances are deposited into the AFF. The interest earned on the AFF balances is the property of the United States Government.”29 The AFF and SADF accounts are maintained at the US Federal Reserve Bank in New York. In accord with statutory requirements, the AFF managers must file an an- nual report with the US Congress detailing areas such as the total net deposits to the fund and the total expenses paid from the fund by category of expense, including equitable-sharing payments. The statute also sets forth the limita- tions governing use of the AFF, and the statutory authority is further con- trolled by policy guidelines.30 In total assets, the AFF (which present as of a specific time the amounts of future economic benefits owned or managed by the AFF/SADF), increased in FY 2011 . . . 71.7 percent . . . [s]pecifically, in FY 2011, ten major fraud cases re- sulted in extraordinary forfeiture income of $733.6 million compared to the nine FY 2010 fraud cases that resulted in extraordinary forfei- ture income of $630.3 million. The term extraordinary is considered nonrecurring forfeiture income greater than $25 million.31 The management and disbursement of forfeited funds must be carried out in a transparent manner. This transparency is necessary not only to preserve the viability of the IASP itself but also to ensure public and global trust in international asset sharing as an effective and accountable tool for reaching development goals. The DOJ’s International Sharing Program The DOJ’s international sharing program32 is “guided by standing interna- tional sharing agreements or [by] the subject of a future case-specific forfeiture sharing arrangement to be negotiated by AFMLS [Asset Forfeiture and Money Laundering Section of the US Department of Justice] and approved by the 29 See Assets Forfeiture Fund and Seized Asset Deposit Fund Annual Financial Statements Fiscal Year 2011, available at http://www.justice.gov/oig/reports/2012/a1212.pdf (accessed Mar. 21, 2012). 30 See Attorney General’s Guidelines on Seized and Forfeited Property (Jul. 1990). 31 See Assets Forfeiture Fund and Seized Asset Deposit Fund Annual Financial Statements Fiscal Year 2011, at 5, available at http://www.justice.gov/oig/reports/2012/a1212.pdf (accessed Mar. 21, 2012). 32 Although not the focus of this chapter, the DOJ also maintains a domestic equitable-sharing program, which as of 2009, had “shared over $4.5 billion in forfeited assets with more than 8,000 state and local law enforcement agencies.” See US Department of Justice, Criminal Division, Guide to Equitable Sharing for State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies (Apr. 2010). http://www.justice.gov/oig/reports/2012/a1212.pdf http://www.justice.gov/oig/reports/2012/a1212.pdf The World Bank Legal Review274 Department of State.”33 When entering into sharing agreements, the DOJ and the recipient country must agree that the funds will be used to strengthen im- portant development goals, such as building capacity in the recipient’s AF/ AML sector. The preference is for shared funds to be used to support AF/AML reform and development; however, with some exceptions, shared funds can be used to support a wide variety of domestic development needs. Regard- less of the ultimate manner in which the funds are spent, each case-specific forfeiture-sharing arrangement is negotiated in a manner designed to ensure that it meets the needs of the recipient country. Between 1992 and 2011, the DOJ, through its international asset-sharing program, shared more than US$234,949,197 with more than 39 countries. Case-Specific Sharing Agreements Countries can enter into case-specific sharing agreements (CSSAs). A CSSA is used when forfeited funds are shared as a result of a specific case.34 Typically, a CSSA is an official written agreement, entered into between two or more coun- tries after a series of negotiations. The CSSA sets forth the percentage of total seized proceeds to be shared, memorializes the mutual understanding of how those proceeds will be used by the recipient country (preferably to enhance its AF/AML regimes), and addresses accountability and transparency issues regarding expenditures. The DOJ’s AFMLS negotiates the terms of the CSSA, with the US Depart- ment of Treasury’s concurrence and the US Department of State’s authoriza- tion. Through this process, the DOJ, often viewed as a domestically focused agency, can exercise a degree of assistance in the international development process. The Process for Requesting a CSSA An assisting country may request a CSSA for DOJ sharing in the following ways: • A request pursuant to a treaty between the United States and the assisting c ountry • A request made within the diplomatic arena • The submission of an official, signed letter by a country’s appropriate rep- resentative addressed to the US law enforcement agency that the country assisted in the investigation 33 US Attorneys Manual, Chapter 9-116.000, Equitable Sharing and Federal Adoption, 9-116.400, International Sharing of Forfeited Assets (2011). 34 In addition to CSSAs, related tools for international asset-sharing agreements are global asset-sharing agreements, which serve the same function as CSSAs, but the terms of which apply to all sharing between two countries, and agreements not limited to a single case agreement (as is a CSSA). International Asset Sharing 275 The Reviewing Process Once the initial request has been received, the appropriate agency in the DOJ will begin the first in a series of reviews to determine if an international as- set-sharing agreement is an appropriate action. The review process normally includes the prosecution office(s) and law enforcement agency (or agencies) that received the foreign assistance and additional divisions within the DOJ. During the review process, the following factors are considered: • Whether the foreign country directly or indirectly participated in the sei- zure or the forfeiture of property • Whether the transfer is authorized in an international agreement (that is, a mutual legal assistance treaty or an asset-sharing agreement) between the United States and the recipient country • Whether the underlying forfeiture has been finalized • Whether the country has been certified under section 481(h) of the US Foreign Assistance Act35 The decision regarding whether to enter into negotiations for a CSSA is not reviewable.36 However, if the above factors have all been satisfied, the pro- cess continues, with additional factors reviewed: • Whether the country provided the information that led to the seizure(s) of property that was ultimately forfeited • Whether the country provided unique and indispensable assistance dur- ing the investigation and prosecution of the case by the DOJ • Whether the country initially identified the assets for seizure • Whether the country seized one or more assets that were forfeited in non- federal proceedings during the same investigation • Whether the country could have pursued forfeiture under domestic law but instead joined forces with the United States to conduct a more effec- tive investigation or prosecution37 Because individual factors may vary, the review process attempts to take into account the totality of circumstances regarding the underlying case, in- cluding recognizing any unique challenges that were present in the investiga- tion and prosecution. 35 Chapter 8, section 481(h) of the Foreign Assistance Act, known as the Certification Law, serves as a link between foreign aid and positive drug-control performance. See http:// www.usaid.gov/policy/ads/faa.pdf (accessed Apr. 3, 2012). 36 The DOJ also shares forfeited proceeds domestically, among US federal, state, and local agencies. As with the global CSSA approach, domestically and pursuant to the Equitable Sharing Program conditions, the percentage of shared funds is based on participation and assistance in the underlying case. 37 US DOJ, Criminal Division, Guide to Equitable Sharing for State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies (Apr. 2010). http://www.usaid.gov/policy/ads/faa.pdf http://www.usaid.gov/policy/ads/faa.pdf The World Bank Legal Review276 How Is the Percentage of Shared Funds Determined? If the DOJ determines that the case is appropriate for international sharing, the next stage is the determination of what percentage of the total amount of forfeited funds will be shared with the assisting country. This determination is at the discretion of the DOJ and typically reflects the degree of assistance provided by the foreign country, which falls into one of three categories: es- sential assistance (EA), major assistance (MA), and facilitating assistance (FA). Essential Assistance The highest level of sharing funds is EA. Cases falling into this category may enter into CSSAs in which 50 to 100 percent of the total forfeited funds can be shared. In deciding what cases fall in the EA category, the DOJ examines fac- tors such as whether the case involved victims or if the assisting country was the victim. In addition, the DOJ considers additional factors such as whether the as- sisting country waived its own forfeiture actions and provided all necessary evidence to US authorities and whether the country initiated defending litiga- tion or agreed to repatriate funds without an account signatory letter. In es- sence, the greater the amount of bilateral cooperation in a case, the greater the percentage of funds shared. Major Assistance In cases deemed to be MA, sharing percentages typically involve 40 to 50 per- cent of the total forfeited amount. In determining whether a case falls into the MA category, the DOJ considers several factors, such as whether the as- sisting country enforced a final forfeiture order from a US court or assisted in repatriating the assets to the United States. Other factors include whether the assisting country aided the US case by freezing or lifting a freeze over as- sets, whether the assisting country repatriated defendants via an extradition request, or whether their law enforcement agents were put at physical risk by assisting in the case. Equally important is whether the assisting country ex- pended substantial prosecutorial and law enforcement resources on the case. A recent example of MA sharing is the March 2012 signing of a letter of intent between the United States and the government of Mexico to share 70 percent, approximately US$6 million. According to a DOJ press release: On March 26, 2012, U.S. Attorney General Eric Holder and Mexican Attorney General Marisela Morales Ibáñez signed a letter of intent for the United States to share approximately $6 million in forfeited funds with the Office of the Attorney General of the Republic of Mexico (PGR) to support Mexican efforts to combat the financial in- frastructure of organized criminal groups and to enhance bilateral cooperation between the two countries in forfeiture matters. The letter of intent and anticipated fund sharing recognized the PGR’s valuable cooperation in the investigation and resolution of the US government’s case against the Sigue Corporation for viola- International Asset Sharing 277 tions of the Bank Secrecy Act. In January 2008, Sigue entered into a deferred prosecution agreement with the Department of Justice on charges of failing to maintain an effective anti-money laundering program. As a result, Sigue forfeited $15 million to the United States and agreed to commit an additional $9.7 million to improving its anti-money laundering program.38 Facilitating Assistance In FA cases, up to 40 percent of the total forfeited funds may be shared. Cases are categorized as FA when the assisting country provided critical informa- tion regarding an investigative lead, assisted the United States by obtaining and sharing extensive bank documentation, provided other financial records, and/or assisted in ensuring that foreign banks repatriated assets. Once the decision regarding the percentage to be shared has been determined, the pro- cess continues to the negotiation stage. Negotiation of CSSA Terms No other US government officer or agency may bind the DOJ to terms of a CSSA, which are negotiated by the AFMLS of the DOJ. For the assisting coun- try, negotiations are typically handled by the corresponding attorney gener- al, minister of justice, or minster of foreign affairs or a representative. The negotiation process includes a series of meetings to discuss how the shared funds will be targeted and addresses mechanisms to ensure accountability and transparency regarding the shared funds. These decisions are arrived at via a process of mutual agreement, and discretion is granted to the assisting country depending on individual circumstances. In discussing areas in which shared funds may be targeted, the domestic AF/AML sector will receive particular attention. The preference is for shared funds to target AF/AML issues; examples include • Support for establishing an AF/AML division with the recipient country’s prosecution office • Funding of joint investigations, programs to identify emerging trends in domestic and regional economic crime sectors, and to strengthen the over- all anti-money-laundering mission of the assisting country • Funding to explore ways to strengthen financial data mining and analysis capacity and to improve the tracking of suspicious bank transactions • Funding initiatives to increase bilateral asset forfeiture cases Typically, the target areas are written into the terms of the CSSA. Although there are some notable exceptions in which shared funds should not be target- ed (such as paying for salaries for prosecutors), the process allows for a great deal of flexibility in determining how funds should be expended. 38 US Department of Justice press release (March 26, 2012). The World Bank Legal Review278 IASPs as a Tool for Development Development has been defined as “the process which facilitates for every hu- man and all persons the enjoyment of economic, social, cultural and political development.”39 This definition includes the critical need to ensure that citi- zens around the globe have both access to and faith in a functioning and trans- parent justice sector. The primary question posed here is exactly how does the adoption and implementation of an IASP contribute to international develop- ment? The answer lies in the ability of the IASP to, if properly implemented, act as a mechanism to support domestic capacity building in a number of dif- ferent areas, including the AF/AML sector, to foster international cooperation, and to provide a means to combat transnational crime. In Resolution 2004/29, the United Nations recognized that the laundering of the proceeds of crime ha[s] spread internationally and ha[s] become a worldwide threat to the stability and security of financial and commercial systems [and] urged Member States that had not yet done so to strengthen their capacity to prevent, control, investigate and suppress serious crimes related to money-laundering, including money-laundering related to the financing of terrorism.40 An IASP can adapt and respond to the specific needs of both the recipient and the sharing country in various ways. First, an IASP can address development needs often encountered in frag- ile or weak states. The ability to target shared funds to specific areas of need can assist fragile states transitioning from postconflict to stable societies. For example, a transparent IASP can assist in the design and implementation of development projects in fragile states by using the shared funds to target key economic and justice sector reforms. It can also effectively address identified constraints that businesses and officials in weak states cite as limitations to growth, such as weak banking and court sectors.41 In these cases, shared mon- ies can provide funding for the establishment of a strong financial intelligence unit, an anticorruption office, or prosecutor and judicial training academies. Second, an effective IASP can provide fragile states with the opportunity to establish or strengthen their AF/AML sectors while also developing key partnerships that enable future capacity-building programs. Third, IASPs can be an effective tool in addressing unique challenges in justice sector growth—such as the absorption challenges that new member 39 Article 1 of the Declaration on the Right to Development (adopted by General Assembly Resolution 41/128 of Dec. 4, 1986), as quoted in A. H. Qureshi & A. R. Ziegler, International Economic Law 494 (2nd ed., Thomson/Sweet & Maxwell 2007). See also http://labspace.open .ac.uk/course/view.php?name=PUB_46_1.2 (accessed Feb. 26, 2012). 40 See 11th United Nations Congress on Crime Prevention and Criminal Justice, Bangkok, 13 (Apr. 2005) (A/CONF.203/1). See also http://www.un.org/events/11thcongress/docs /programme.pdf (accessed Mar. 12, 2012). 41 See http://www.cgdev.org/content/publications/detail/1426232 (accessed Jul. 18, 2012). http://labspace.open.ac.uk/course/view.php?name=PUB_46_1.2 http://labspace.open.ac.uk/course/view.php?name=PUB_46_1.2 http://www.un.org/events/11thcongress/docs/programme.pdf http://www.cgdev.org/content/publications/detail/1426232 http://www.un.org/events/11thcongress/docs/programme.pdf International Asset Sharing 279 states of the European Union must confront. For example, shared funds can be focused on assisting new member states in their efforts to address economic, institutional, and justice sector absorption challenges, such as the need to im- prove fiscal management practices and to strengthen anticorruption capaci- ties. In these areas, an IASP can act as a mechanism to assist new member states in overcoming obstacles while continuing to foster key partnerships and encourage innovative planning initiatives. Fourth, IASPs can serve overall global development goals by strengthen- ing international cooperation efforts among countries, regardless of the eco- nomic or legal differences that may separate them. By serving as a mechanism that encourages countries to work together, IASPs create global partnerships to prevent, control, investigate, and suppress transnational economic crime. Finally, an accountable and transparent IASP demonstrates, at a very pub- lic and visible level, the ability of governments to work globally to take profits away from criminals and redirect them back to the very agencies and offices tasked with combating economic crimes. In a related manner, the successful completion of a bilateral CSSA represents an opportunity to share, domesti- cally and internationally, the message that international cooperation in fight- ing economic crime not only occurs but, more important, succeeds. Conclusion The ever-increasing globalization of transnational criminal groups not only endangers global economic systems but also undermines rule of law and good governance practices. Encouraged by the United Nations and domestic gov- ernments alike, asset sharing at an international level is an effective and pow- erful tool for development. It can assist in disrupting and dismantling trans- national criminal organizations while strengthening international cooperation on AF/AML issues.42 The ability of countries to cooperate on a bilateral scale and enter into mutually beneficial asset-sharing agreements serves a number of goals, including “taking the profit out of crime.” 42 DOJ equitable sharing applies only to sharing of assets that were seized by the DOJ and that were “forfeited judicially or administratively to the United States by the United States Attorney’s Offices or Forfeiture Program Participants.” The participants include the Asset Forfeiture and Money Laundering Section, Criminal Division (AFMLS); Organized Crime Drug Enforcement Task Force (OCDETF); Asset Forfeiture Management Staff, Justice Man- agement Division (AFMS); Bureau of Alcohol, Tobacco, Firearms and Explosives (ATF); Defense Criminal Investigative Service (DCIS); Drug Enforcement Administration (DEA); Bureau of Diplomatic Security, Department of State (DS); Executive Office for United States Attorneys (EOUSA); Federal Bureau of Investigation (FBI); Food and Drug Administration (FDA), United States Department of Agriculture (USDA); United States Marshals Service (USMS); and United States Postal Service (USPS). See US DOJ, Criminal Division, Guide to Equitable Sharing for State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies (Apr. 2010). Toward a New Law and Development New State Activism in Brazil and the Challenge for Legal Institutions DaviD M. Trubek, Diogo r. CouTinho, anD Mario g. SChapiro At the intersection of law, economics, and the practices of states and devel- opment agencies, the field of law and development undergoes continuous realignment.1 As economic policies, legal theories, and institutional practices change, the salient issues in law and development change as well.2 The 21st century has ushered in a new era. Development theories are being challenged and new practices are emerging. Law and development scholars need to un- derstand the new trends and explore their implications for legal studies and practice. In the past couple of decades, development policy and practice have shift- ed in many regions, but nowhere more clearly than in Latin America. After a long period when neoliberal policies prevailed and the state’s role in the economy was curtailed, many countries in the region have begun to explore new forms of state activism. Brazil has been a leader in the formation of new development policies and in the creation of a new development discourse. Starting with the election of Lula da Silva in 2002 and gaining momentum during Lula’s second term in 2006, Brazil has instituted new forms of indus- trial and social policy, experienced a surge in growth, and seen a reduction in economic inequality. This trend has led scholars to begin to talk about a “new developmen- talism” and speculate about the emergence of a new kind of developmental state in which the government plays an active role in mobilizing resources, stimulating investment, and promoting innovation but does not command or 1 This article draws on David M. Trubek, Diogo R. Coutinho, and Mario G. Schapiro, New State Activism in Brazil and the Challenge for Law, in Law and the New Developmental State: The Bra- zilian Experience in Latin American Context (David M. Trubek et al. ed., Cambridge U. Press, forthcoming) (hereinafter, Trubek et. al). An earlier version of the article was discussed at the 2012 IGLP Workshop at Harvard Law School and the Conference on Global Governance: Critical Legal Perspectives at the European University Institute (July, 2012). The authors are grateful to Peter Houtzager, Willy Forbath, Alvaro Santos, David Kennedy, Duncan Ken- nedy, Helena Alviar, Jeremy Perelman, Lucie White, Mushtaq Kahn, Shunko Rojas, and Yves Dezalay for comments and suggestions. The authors also received useful comments from Professor Wang Chenguang of the Tsinghua University School of Law. 2 For a discussion of the history of law and development, see David M. Trubek and Alvaro San- tos, The New Law and Economic Development: A Critical Appraisal (Cambridge U. Press 2006). 281 The World Bank Legal Review282 control the economy. In this approach, the state employs an open-economy industrial policy to restructure production and increase international compe- tiveness while simultaneously using an active social policy to eliminate pov- erty, reduce inequality, and stimulate domestic demand. Unlike the old para- digm, in this new model, such a state seeks to benefit from participation in the global economy while avoiding the dangers of free trade fundamentalism, and it tries to stimulate, not replace, the private sector.3 This chapter explores shifts in government policy in Brazil since 2000, showing how these changes are influencing developments in the law. After a limited experience with neoliberalism, the country has embraced new forms of state engagement in the economy and social relations. Because these chang- es are recent and have not yet been fully consolidated, the resulting constella- tion can be viewed as new state activism (NSA),4 a term that suggests neither a return to the past nor a clearly consolidated alternative “model.” The chapter covers the emergence of NSA; identifies its salient features, noting how it dif- fers from prior forms of state intervention; explores some of the forces that have shaped this new form of state action; and provides a preliminary assess- ment of the significance and challenge of these developments for the law. Introduction: From the “Long 1990s” (1988–2004) to NSA The evolution of NSA in Brazil was preceded by a series of policy changes that dismantled some of the institutions of the old developmental state and embraced some aspects of the Washington Consensus. Like several other developing Latin American countries, Brazil had a classic developmentalist phase in the twentieth century: from 1930 until the end of the 1980s, economic policies consisted of state-led initiatives to promote import substitution indus- trialization, and growth through state-owned enterprises, economic planning, price control, regulatory and administrative authorities in key sectors, and the use of tax and financial incentives. 3 For a discussion of new developmentalism and the idea of a new development state, see David M. Trubek, Law, State and the New Developmentalism: An Introduction, in Trubek et. al, supra note 1. 4 See Glauco Arbix & Scott B. Martin, Beyond Developmentalism and Market Fundamental- ism in Brazil: Inclusionary State Activism without Statism, paper presented at the workshop on “States, Development, and Global Governance,” Global Legal Studies Center and the Center for World Affairs and the Global Economy (WAGE), University of Wisconsin, 2010, available at http://www.law.wisc.edu/gls/documents/paper_arbix.pdf (accessed Jul. 15, 2012); and Renato Boschi, Estado Desenvolvimentista no Brasil: Continuidades e incertidumbres (2010), 2 Ponto de Vista, available at http://neic.iesp.uerj.br/pontodevista/pdf/Ponto_de_ Vista_01fev2010.pdf (accessed Oct. 10, 2010). For an account of “new developmentalism” in Brazil, see Luiz Carlos Bresser-Pereira, From Old to New Developmentalism in Latin America, in Textos para Discussão–Escola de Economia de São Paulo 193 (2009). See also Eli Diniz, É possível um Novo Modelo de Estado Desenvolvimentista no Brasil? 2 IPEA – Boletim de Análise Político- Instiutional 17 (2012). http://www.law.wisc.edu/gls/documents/paper_arbix.pdf http://neic.iesp.uerj.br/pontodevista/pdf/Ponto_de_Vista_01fev2010.pdf http://neic.iesp.uerj.br/pontodevista/pdf/Ponto_de_Vista_01fev2010.pdf Toward a New Law and Development 283 Between 1988 and 2004, known as the “long 1990s,” Brazil partially dis- mantled these structures and policies and shifted to more market-oriented ap- proaches. In 1988, after 24 years of military dictatorship and in a context of a threat of hyperinflation,5 Brazil passed a new constitution that has influenced and shaped policy ever since. The 1988 constitution is a social democratic doc- ument that created a vibrant democratic polity and includes civil, political, and social rights and a number of policy goals such as building a free, just, and socially integrated society; fostering national development; acquiring tech- nological autonomy; eradicating poverty and marginalization; and reducing economic and social inequalities. Many of the constitution’s provisions have had a direct effect on government policy and budgetary allocations. President Collor de Mello was elected in 1989, immediately after the new constitution came into force. Stressing the need for “modernization,” Col- lor de Mello rapidly liberalized the economy using drastic tariff reductions, privatization, and flawed attempts to control inflation. Under Itamar Franco, who replaced Collor de Mello after he was impeached, a stabilization plan (the Plano Real) was successfully adopted and inflation was controlled.6 New legislation on social assistance and welfare for the poor was also passed. Franco’s minister of finance, Fernando Henrique Cardoso (known as FHC), became the next president in 1994. During Cardoso’s eight years in of- fice, Brazil continued to move away from the dirigiste policies of the develop- mentalist period, embracing many of the neoliberal prescriptions favored by the Washington Consensus.7 In the Cardoso period, state owned-enterprises were privatized, direct subsidies for certain industries were scaled back, areas of the economy were deregulated, import barriers were reduced, competition was fostered and enforced, intellectual property rights were tightened, bilat- eral investment treaties protecting foreign investors were signed, and fiscal responsibility was enhanced. Also, the currency (the real) was constantly kept overvalued as monetary stability was pursued and attained.8 Under Cardoso, the bureaucracy was partially modernized, regulatory agencies were created, public-private partnerships were designed, and new 5 In January 1990, inflation in Brazil reached 56 percent per month, raising to 73 percent in February and peaking at 84 percent in March; see Luiz Carlos Bresser-Pereira and Yoshiaki Nakano, Hiperinflação e estabilização no Brasil: O Primeiro Plano Collor, Revista de Economia Política 4 (1991). During the same period, economic inequality reached its worse level since it had been measured (the Gini coefficient peaked at 0.647, according to the Brazilian Office of Statistics). 6 “Despite that, a period of strong deterioration of the Balance of Payments began, which led the current-account deficit to achieve 4.0% of the GDP in 1998.” Antonio Barros de Castro, From Semi-Stagnation to Growth in a Sino-Centric Market, 28 Brazilian J. of Pol. Eco. 3–27 (2008). 7 Cardoso has always rejected the neoliberal label and claimed that his goal simply was to modernize the economy. 8 “[T]he goal of price stability has remained sacrosanct and the instruments for achieving this goal have been in line with the latest international fashions: central bank independence and inflation targeting.” Cornel Ban, Brazil’s Liberal Neo-Developmentalism: New Paradigm or Edited Orthodoxy? Rev. Intl. of Pol. Eco. (forthcoming). The World Bank Legal Review284 social policies were adopted. To carry out privatization and encourage foreign investment, Congress made several changes in the constitution. But although the country adopted some ideas from the Washington Consensus, it did not wholeheartedly embrace neoliberalism. Privatizations were limited; Banco do Brasil, BNDES (the Brazilian Development Bank), and Petrobrás, three major state-owned enterprises, remained under government control. None of the bilateral investment treaties signed in the 1990s was ratified. Institutional and Political Background: The New Democratic Constitution of 1988 and the Cardoso Administration Political parties and social movements had been repressed during military rule (1964–85). When the constitution-making process started in the late 1980s, an eruption of social-political demands had to be accommodated. Not surpris- ingly, the resulting constitution was nicknamed “the citizen’s constitution.” Not only did it create democratic institutions, it also included an extensive charter of civil-political and social rights and reframed public-private rela- tionships. The constitution incorporates provisions guaranteeing the rule of law, protecting individual rights, and guarding against arbitrary state action. It also created positive—and justiciable—rights that could impose policy ob- ligations. The 1988 constitution includes rights to health, education, housing, social protection, and pensions. These guarantees have shaped a new and complex welfare system, including a massive universal public health system and a system of universal pensions. The new system in turn has had a ma- jor impact on the role of the state and on patterns of government spending.9 Instead of cutting back on social spending as many countries did during the 1990s, Brazil increased the percentage of GDP devoted to social protection during that period.10 Besides facilitating political mobilization and participation, instituting so- cial rights and shaping social policies, the new constitution facilitated modern- ization of the state apparatus and reframed public-private relationships with consequences for the business environment. The 1988 constitution initiated a slow process of professionalizing state administration. Until the 1930s, public employees were hired through the “spoils system” of political appointments. A partial reform under Getulio Vargas had instituted meritocratic selection for some key agencies such as BNDES and the Foreign Ministry, but left most gov- ernment jobs subject to political appointment.11 The 1988 constitution carried 9 See Jorge Abrahão de Castro & José Celso Cardoso Jr., Políticas Sociais no Brasil: Gasto Social do Governo Federal de 1988 a 2002, in Questão Social e Políticas Sociais no Brasil Contemporâneo (Luciana Jacoud et. al. ed., IPEA 2005). 10 See Kleber Pacheco de Castro & José Roberto Afonso, Gasto Social no Brasil Pós 1988: Uma Análise sob a Ótica da Descentralização Fiscal, 1 Revista de Política, Planejamento e Gestão da Saúde 34–56 (2009). 11 The first initiative to reform the public sector to create a more professional public staff was un- der taken by President Getulio Vargas (1930–45), whose government created the Department Toward a New Law and Development 285 the reform further, requiring that all public employees be selected through meritocratic processes and capping state salaries. The constitution significantly affected relations between the state and business. It required competitive bidding for all state purchases and made the process more transparent. The special federal prosecutors (Ministério Público) were authorized to combat corruption and enforce laws protecting consumers and the environment. The constitution also protected individuals and busi- nesses against regulatory takings and expropriation without compensation. Although the new constitution embraced social-democratic values and norms and some developmentalist ideas, during the 1990s, Brazil flirted with neoliberal policies. In 1994, President Itamar Franco and Minister of Finance Fernando Henrique Cardoso launched the Plano Real, a macroeconomic sta- bilization effort that eventually managed to control inflation in Brazil.12 One of Cardoso’s first acts as president was to get Congress to remove some provi- sions in the 1988 constitution that enshrined “old developmentalist” policies such as state monopolies and restrictions on foreign investment.13 Under Cardoso, Brazil experienced a strong devaluation of the real as a result of a harsh international crisis (particularly in Mexico, Russia, and Asia). The government raised the interest rate to a very high level, which severely hindered growth. At the same time, the Cardoso government managed to embed Brazil in the world economy through trade liberalization. In 2000, it ensured fiscal austerity by passing a fiscal responsibility act, and it sought to modernize public administration by adopting tenets of a “new public admin- istration” that allowed outsourcing of certain functions to the private sector.14 Under Cardoso, Brazil accelerated privatizations initiated by Collor and Itamar Franco:15 in 1997, Vale do Rio Doce, a major state-owned mining and steelmaking company, and Sistema Telebrás, the public-owned telecommu- nication conglomerate, were sold. In the same year, several electricity and gas distribution companies, as well as some state-level banks, were trans- ferred to private owners. During his eight years as president, Cardoso raised of Public Service Management (DASP), a preliminary attempt at establishing a public career path in Brazil. 12 In 1999, Brazil officially adopted an inflation target system (the target in 2012 is 4.5 percent per year). 13 João Paulo M. Peixoto, The Brazilian States since Vargas, in The Brazilian State: Debate and Agenda (Mauricio Font & Laura Randall ed., Lexington Books, 2011). 14 The strategy segregated core activities that should be performed by politicians and senior officials, including conducting support activities that may be outsourced, separating policy formulation from policy execution, and granting more autonomy and accountability to ser- vices performed by the state, which would take the form of either “executive agencies” or of “social organizations” that are a special type of nonprofit. See Luiz Carlos Bresser-Pereira, The 1995 Public Management Reform in Brazil: Reflections of a Reformer, in Reinventing Leviathan: The Politics of Administrative Reform in Developing Countries (Ben Ross Schneider & Blanca Heredia, ed., North-South Center Press, 2003). 15 Franco privatized CNS, an important steel company, in 1995. The World Bank Legal Review286 approximately US$79 billion through privatization. However, like Petrobrás, the Brazilian state oil and gas company, the three large federal banks—Banco do Brasil, Caixa Econômica Federal, and BNDES—were not privatized. In- deed, BNDES played an important role in facilitating privatization by offering credit to both domestic and international buyers. Table 1 lists the state-owned enterprises that were privatized in the 1990s. Table 1. State-Owned Enterprises Privatized USIMINAS 24.10.1991 CSN 02.04.1993 USIMEC 24.10.1991 FEM 02.04.1993 CELMA 01.11.1991 ULTRAFÉRTIL 24.06.1993 MAFERSA 11.11.1991 COSIPA 20.08.1993 COSINOR 14.11.1991 AÇOMINAS 10.09.1993 COSINOR DIST. 14.11.1991 EAC 07.12.1994 SNBP 14.01.1992 EAI 07.12.1994 AFP 14.02.1992 PQU 25.01.1994 PETROFLEX 10.04.1992 CARAÍBA 28.07.1994 COPESUL 15.05.1992 EMBRAER 07.12.1994 Can 15.07.1992 NEIVA 07.12.1994 ALCANORTE 15.07.1992 ESCELSA 11.07.1995 CST 23.07.1992 LIGHT 21.05.1996 FOSFÉRTIL 12.08.1992 VALE 06.05.1997 GOIASFÉRTIL 08.10.1992 MERIDIONAL 04.12.1997 ACESITA 23.10.1992 TELEBRÁS 29.07.1998 ENERGÉTICA 23.10.1992 GERASUL 15.09.1998 FASA 23.10.1992 DATAMEC 23.06.1999 Source: Ministério do Planejamento, Orçamento e Gestão (Brazil) Brazil adapted the US model of regulatory agencies to supervise and en- force post-privatization rules and to introduce competition in natural monop- olies. As a result, electrical distribution, fixed telecommunication networks, and transportation (railways, highways, waterways) were subject to a new legal and institutional framework that substantively changed the patterns of administrative law. New licensing and concession agreements were signed. For a list of areas subjected to regulation see table 2. Toward a New Law and Development 287 Table 2. Activity Regulated Activity Regulated Commission Foundation Law Competition CADE 1994 8.884/94 Electric power ANEEL 1996 9.427/96 Oil & Gas ANP 1997 9.478/97 Telecommunication ANATEL 1997 9.472/97 Health Surveillance ANVISA 1999 9.782/99 Health Insurance ANS 2000 9.961/00 Water ANA 2000 9.984/00 Water Transport ANTAQ 2001 10.233/01 Land Transport ANTT 2001 10.233/01 Aviation ANAC 2005 11.182/05 The Cardoso administration rejected the idea of industrial policy, long a mainstay of Brazil’s developmental state. Finance Minister Pedro Malan said that “the best industrial policy you can have is not to have one.” BNDES, which for decades had provided financing to targeted sectors and supported many state-owned enterprises, shifted to support of privatization. Rather than trying to support priority sectors, the government focused on increasing the efficiency of government services and reforming credit markets. For example, starting with Cardoso and continuing into Lula’s first term, the Central Bank sought to reduce the cost of credit. Among the microeconomic measures un- dertaken were improvements in bankruptcy procedures and debt collection.16 The Cardoso administration’s opposition to industrial policy did not de- ter it from stimulating selected sectors in order to promote competiveness and innovation. Thus, in 1999, 16 new sectorial funds were charged with fostering innovation in strategic areas such as oil and gas, telecommunications, biotech- nology, and agribusiness. The Cardoso period also saw important changes in social policy. Traditionally, the Brazilian welfare state has been regressive, cli- entelistic, and opaque. Between 1994 and 2002, the federal government took a number of measures aimed at transforming this system, including add- ing poverty-alleviation programs aimed at specific populations; introduc- ing noncontributory social protection programs; decentralizing social policy implementation; and tackling some of the regressive features of the pension 16 According to Fabiani, during the 1999–2006 period, the law behind the government’s micro- economic agenda was seen as an instrument to protect creditors and ultimately to promote economic efficiency. See Emerson Ribeiro Fabiani, Direito e Crédito Bancário no Brasil (Saraiva, FGV, 2011). The World Bank Legal Review288 scheme.17 The Cardoso government initiated the use of conditional cash trans- fers; for example, the Bolsa Escola program, implemented 2001, aimed to in- crease access to education, reduce poverty in the short term by transferring cash to impoverished households, reduce child labor, and serve as a social protection network.18 Another important development in this period was LOAS (the Social As- sistance Act). Enacted under Itamar Franco and implemented by Cardoso, LOAS seeks to guarantee “minimum social standards.” The noncontributory multilevel federal, state, and local program is designed to protect households, mothers, children, adolescents, and the elderly; to assist underprivileged chil- dren and adolescents; to promote labor market integration; and to train and rehabilitate persons with disabilities and promote their integration into com- munity life.19 NSA Emerges Luiz Inácio Lula da Silva was elected president in 2002. For two four-year terms, his government preserved some Cardoso policies such as inflation control and openness to foreign investment while changing others by adopt- ing state-activist initiatives, including an active industrial policy and a mas- sive poverty-fighting program. Dilma Roussef, elected president in 2010, has maintained Lula’s priorities but expanded state activism in key areas.20 Lula’s inauguration instigated a decade of experimentation. Develop- mentalist institutions have been reinvented, neoliberal policies were modi- fied, new institutions were created, and a new form of state activism is emerg- ing. Changes have occurred gradually.21 Some of Cardoso’s policies, such as 17 Almeida explains that during Cardoso’s first term, some changes in universal social polices confronted the regressive feature of the Brazilian pension system (a constitutional amend- ment changed the minimum age and the period of contribution for retirement), although the problematic topic of public servants’ pensions—a major source of inequality in the coun- try—remained untouched. See Maria Hermínia Tavares de Almeida, A Política Social no Go- verno Lula, 70 Novos Estudos - CEBRAP 70 7–17 (2004). 18 Inspired by successful experiences at the local level, the federal Bolsa Escola program reached more than 5 million families. Other conditional cash transfer programs widened the scope of protection and helped build a multilevel public-private network of providers. 19 The federal government is assigned the task of coordinating and promoting LOAS and pro- viding technical advice and financial incentives to states, cities, and welfare entities and organizations. States must transfer certain funds to municipalities, provide them with tech- nical support, and stimulate the collective rendering of social services. Municipalities must, among other things, execute social assistance and poverty-fighting policies, which includes the possibility of establishing partnerships with civil society organizations. 20 See Alfredo Saad Filho, Neo-Developmentalism and the Challenges of Economic Policy-Making under Dilma Rousseff, 38 Critical Sociology (2012), available at http://crs.sagepub.com/con- tent/early/2012/07/03/0896920512441635.abstract?rss=1 (accessed Oct. 5, 2012). 21 To win the election, Lula stated that debt agreements would be honored. Talking about the gradual manner through which changes would take place, Lula said in his “Letter to Bra- zilians” in 2002: “the premise of this transition will naturally be the respect to contracts http://crs.sagepub.com/content/early/2012/07/03/0896920512441635.abstract?rss=1 http://crs.sagepub.com/content/early/2012/07/03/0896920512441635.abstract?rss=1 Toward a New Law and Development 289 macroeconomic stabilization, have been preserved, and some of his social policy innovations have been improved and substantially expanded. Institu- tions like BNDES that survived from the period of state developmentalism have been reinvigorated and redirected. Other developmentalist institutions, such as industrial policy, that were rejected during the neoliberal period have been revived, albeit in different form. Finally, new institutions have been added to increase coordination between the public and private sectors.22 Macroeconomic Continuity Scarred by decades of high and damaging inflation, Brazil adopted policies in the 1990s to preserve monetary stability. The Plano Real used various mea- sures to control public spending and regulate the money supply. This has kept the inflation rate low (by Brazilian standards) for more than 15 years and en- shrined monetary stability as a cornerstone of economic policy. During the first Lula administration, emphasis was placed on instituting, developing, and strengthening political and economic credibility using fiscally responsible macroeconomic policy, a floating exchange rate, and inflation targeting. In gen- eral terms, the Dilma administration has continued these policies. However, this emphasis has come at a price: the main tools of macroeconomic policy are restrictions on government spending and a relatively high interest rate, putting a brake on public investment and increasing the cost of credit, thus possibly hampering growth. To offset these effects, Lula introduced several growth-inducing microeconomic policies, including a new form of industrial policy and social policies that helped spur domestic growth while relieving poverty and reducing economic inequality. Industrial Policy In 2004, after a decade in which Brazil had explicitly rejected industrial policy,23 the government introduced measures designed to foster selected in- dustries. Lula’s first try at industrial policy was limited and focused primarily on innovation. At the time, there was strong opposition to industrial policy in policy making circles and academic opinion. It was thought that governments were not able to strategically identify targets and that trying to do so would divert resources from horizontal structural measures such as tax reform and infrastructure investment that would benefit the entire economy. However, some people were prepared to accept a limited role for govern- ment in overcoming market failures and reducing the coordination and sys- temic problems that hampered innovation; the Cardoso administration had taken modest steps in this direction. Lula’s first foray into industrial policy and obligations enforceable in the country.” Available at http://www2.fpa.org.br/carta-ao- povo-brasileiro-por-luiz-inacio-lula-da-silva. 22 A notable example is the Public-Private Partnership Federal Act of 2004. 23 For a history of the rejection of industrial policy see Wilson Suzigan & A. V. Villela, Industrial Policy in Brazil (Editora da Unicamp 1997). http://www2.fpa.org.br/carta-ao-povo-brasileiro-por-luiz-inacio-lula-da-silva http://www2.fpa.org.br/carta-ao-povo-brasileiro-por-luiz-inacio-lula-da-silva The World Bank Legal Review290 —called PITCE—stressed a combination of general measures to improve the business environment24 and financial support in four sectors in which one could argue innovation was essential: semiconductors, software, capital goods, and medicines. PITCE included substantial legislative activity, including the Innova- tion Law (designed to facilitate partnerships and synergy among universi- ties, companies, and research institutes) and the Foundation Law (which fa- cilitated government support for university research).25 At the same time, the government started building institutions designed to improve coordination within government and between government and the private sector. These in- cluded the Council of Economic and Social Development (CDES), designed to help foster inclusive growth; the National Council of Industrial Development (CNDI), a public-private body charged with defining directives for industrial development; and the Brazilian Agency for Industrial Development (ABDI), which coordinates implementation of industrial policy by bringing together government, industry, labor, and universities. Arbix and Martin describe ABDI as a “networked institution, formally under the Ministry of Develop- ment, Industry, and Trade. ABDI has played an important role in seeking to develop an industrial policy and helps identify and guides investment deci- sions in technological research, innovation and industrial development.”26 In 2008, during Lula’s second term, the government launched the Pro- gram for Productive Development (PDP).27 PDP replaced PITCE and was much more ambitious and complex. It included both horizontal measures designed to increase the overall efficiency of the economy and vertical pro- grams for targeted sectors. Reflecting the scope and complexity of the Brazil- ian economy, PDP covered a wide range of industries. The program set goals, established a complex governance regime, and placed special emphasis on collaboration between the public and the private sectors. It called for industry- specific competiveness councils instituted by Cardoso and expanded under Lula. PDP relied on policy instruments such as financing, tax, public procure- ment, public-private alliances, coordination and consultation, and regulation. Horizontal measures in PDP included improvements in infrastructure and education, increased investments in science, reductions in interest rates for investment, tax relief, and improvements in the legal environment, including 24 These include legal measures to improve incentives for innovation and to facilitate better relations between universities and business, as well as tax relief. 25 The Innovation Law allowed the government to invest directly in private companies as a mi- nority shareholder in order to create new products and processes, and provides for sharing of any resulting intellectual property. The Foundation Law facilitated support from FINEP and the National Fund for Scientific and Technological Development for university-based research-support foundations. 26 Arbix & Martin, supra note 4. 27 The discussion in this section draws heavily on Luciano Coutinho et al., “Industrial Policy and Economic Transformation,” in The Oxford Handbook of Latin American Political Economy, 134–188 (Javier Santiso & Jeff Dayton-Johnson ed., Oxford U. Press, 2012). Toward a New Law and Development 291 modernizing the rules governing foreign trade. Vertical measures, which dealt with specific industries, were designed to meet three basic challenges. For each, there were different governance mechanisms and a different mix of policies and measures. Measures that might be employed included subsidized credit from BNDES and other public financial sources, tax incentives, technical as- sistance, advantages in public procurement rules, favorable trade policy, and supportive regulation. The first challenge identified by PDP was to consolidate and expand lead- ership in sectors in which Brazil was deemed to have a competitive edge. The goal was to support Brazilian firms that could be world leaders or heavy- weights in their industry. Sectors included aviation, mining, steel, cellulose, oil and gas/petrochemical, bioethanol, and meat. The second challenge was to foster and occasionally induce mergers and alliances (sometimes with BNDES holding a minority stake) to build up industries that had competitive potential but were not yet at the global frontier. These included capital goods, the auto- motive complex, wood and furniture, pharmaceutical, meatpacking, personal hygiene, perfumery and cosmetics, construction, various service industries, coastal and marine industry, leather, footwear and artifacts, the agro-industri- al system, and plastics. The third challenge was to strengthen high-tech “van- guard” sectors that had both growth potential and whose growth could im- prove the technological capacity of the entire economy. These strategic areas included health, biotechnology, defense, nuclear energy, nanotechnology, and information and communication technology. The governance of PDP was complex. A system of public management brings representatives of appropriate ministries and agencies together for each of the major tasks and links them to the private sector through a variety of coordination devices. Observers of PDP point to the importance of public- private coordination at every level, from setting overall priorities to working out packages of effective measures for each sector. PDP was overtaken by the global financial crisis before it got off the ground. But even if there had been no recession, a program like this, which en- visions major structural changes, must be considered in a long-term context. Although the government can point to some real achievements, critics have questioned whether the plan truly shifted resources from traditional sectors to high-tech industries or if did enough for small and medium industry, which often is a major source of innovation.28 In 2011, the new administration, led by Dilma Rouseff, introduced an updated version of PDP called Brasil Maior (Greater Brazil) with the motto 28 According to information available from the BNDES, in 2008, out of the 179 beneficiary companies, 12 were listed in Bovespa (a Brazilian stock exchange). In 2009, out of the 156 beneficiary companies, 25 were listed in Bovespa. Available at http://www.bndes.gov.br /SiteBNDES/bndes/bndes_pt/Institucional/BNDES_Transparente/Consulta_as_operacoes _do_BNDES (accessed May 1, 2010). http://www.bndes.gov.br/SiteBNDES/bndes/bndes_pt/Institucional/BNDES_Transparente/Consulta_as_operacoes_do_BNDES http://www.bndes.gov.br/SiteBNDES/bndes/bndes_pt/Institucional/BNDES_Transparente/Consulta_as_operacoes_do_BNDES http://www.bndes.gov.br/SiteBNDES/bndes/bndes_pt/Institucional/BNDES_Transparente/Consulta_as_operacoes_do_BNDES The World Bank Legal Review292 “innovate to compete; compete to grow.”29 This plan continued many of the same objectives and policies of PDP. But reflecting rising concerns about “dein- dustrialization,” the plan emphasizes efforts to protect domestic industries hit hard by global competition, an overvalued currency, and low-cost imports. Taxes on manufacturing have been reduced, attention is paid to antidump- ing measures, and substantial preferences for local producers in government procurement have been introduced. At the same time, funding from BNDES and FINEP, the Financiadora de Estudos e Projetos, were increased and efforts were made to channel more funding to innovative firms and sectors. ABDI identifies three major strategic areas for development and explains how Brasil Maior addresses each area. To increase investment and spur inno- vation, Brasil Maior offers tax relief, increased financing for investment and innovation, and further improvements in the legal framework. To promote ex- ports and protect domestic industry from unfair trade, the plan offers tax re- lief, export financing and guarantees, trade promotion, and enhanced defense thorough antidumping and other trade remedies. To protect hard-hit domestic firms, the plan includes exemptions from payroll tax for selected industries and a 25 percent margin of preference for local firms in government procurement. An important part of the Brasil Maior plan is the system of public-private coordination that builds on structures created for PDP: the National Industrial Development Council (CNDI), sectorial executive committees, and sectorial competiveness councils. CNDI is a peak institution that includes ministers, the president of BNDES, and 18 representatives of industry, labor, and the public. Its role is to set strategic guidelines. The Brasil Maior plan identifies 20 priority sectors: petroleum, gas and marine construction, chemicals, health, renewable energy, furniture, automotive, mining, civil construction, defense, aviation and aerospace, agro-industry, capital goods, metallurgy, logistics ser- vices, electronics, personal hygiene, fragrances and cosmetics (HPPC), servic- es, retail, shoes, textiles, candy and jewelry, cellulose and paper. There is an ex- ecutive committee and a competiveness council for each sector. The executive committee consists of government officials charged with developing an action plan for the sector. These representatives meet with the sectorial competive- ness councils to refine the action plans and explore implementation issues. Social Policy In addition to reviving industrial policy, the governments of Lula and Dilma have expanded Brazil’s social protection system and antipoverty programs. The result is a significant decline in the poverty rate, a reduction in inequality, substantial growth of the middle class, and stimulus for the domestic mar- ket. Between 2001 and 2008, incomes of the wealthy grew at a moderate pace, while the income of the poor increased substantively. Approximately 28 mil- lion people moved out of poverty and a “new” middle class has emerged— between 2003 and 2011 approximately 10.5 million Brazilians became part of 29 Available at http://www.brasilmaior.mdic.gov.br/. http://www.brasilmaior.mdic.gov.br/ Toward a New Law and Development 293 the middle class, which now includes 55 percent of the population.30 The Bra- zilian social pyramid is now diamond shaped, with more citizens classified as middle class than as poor. The distributive gains achieved in Brazil during the past decade are the result of a combination of economic and institutional reforms. These reforms include the reintroduction of previous efforts such as inflation control and changes in labor markets that include unemployment reduction and increases in the minimum wage, pensions, and social security improvements, as well as a new generation of social assistance policies, especially the Bolsa Família program (BFP), created in 2003 as a result of a consolidation of previously existing initiatives.31 Health and education spending as a share of GDP has grown considerably in recent years, magnifying the impacts of institutional reforms instituted in the late 1990s. In another recent development, in 2011, the Brazilian Unified Social Assistance System (SUAS) was institutionalized and formalized by a federal statute. In June 2011, President Dilma Rousseff launched the Brasil Sem Miséria program,32 designed to rescue 16.2 million people from extreme poverty, 59 percent of whom live in the northeast region. Brasil Sem Miséria has been presented as a combination of complementary rural and urban sectorial ac- tions—in the areas of income transfer, labor market integration, access to public services, education, health, social assistance, water, and sewage—and involves the creation of new initiatives and the reconceptualization of exist- ing ones. This program aims to find and register extremely poor families and integrate them into different programs. Brasil Sem Miséria is also supposed to help those who graduate from BFP enter the labor market.33 The changes in social policy seem to be working: poverty has been cut drastically and income inequality has been reduced. Although Brazil still is one of the most economically unequal countries in the world,34 the decline in pov- erty and the reduction of inequality in Brazil in recent years have been remark- able. Thanks to a wide range of policies—including universal, targeted, and decentralized programs—the Brazilian welfare state is becoming stronger.35 30 See Marcelo Nery, A Nova Classe Média – o lado brilhante da base da pirâmide 29 (Saraiva 2011). 31 Since its inception, BFP has reached more than 12 million families as beneficiaries. If one as- sumes that each family has four people on average, the total figure for individuals who have benefited from BFP reaches 48 million people, or approximately 25 percent of the Brazilian population. Half of its budget has been spent in the northeast part of Brazil, where millions of very poor families live. Considering its gigantic scale, the targeting of BFP (defined as the share of total benefits received by specific groups of the population) has been considered ex- emplary, outperforming other social assistance programs in both Brazil and internationally. 32 Translation: “Brazil without Indigence.” 33 Brasil Sem Miséria also changed the number of children and adolescents who can obtain the BFP benefit—as of 2012, up to five (it used to be three). 34 The Brazilian Gini coefficient in 1960 was 0.5367; it was 0.6091 in 1990; and in 2010, it was still very high (0.5304). See Nery, supra note 30 at 27. 35 As put by Arbix & Martin, supra note 4: “while Brazil’s ‘welfare state’ still has segmented The World Bank Legal Review294 Brazil’s NSA: Something New under the Sun? The emerging profile of state activism differs from state action in both the developmentalist period and the neoliberal phase of the 1990s. In the devel- opmentalist period, from the 1930s to the 1980s, the Brazilian government not only set priorities for industrialization in a top-down fashion, it also was a primary actor in industry. The state bureaucracy set goals; state-owned enter- prises played a central role in many sectors, including steel, mining, aircraft, automobiles, and banking; and the state development bank provided funding for areas deemed priority by government planners. Emphasis was on “catch- ing up” by building domestic industries. The new industries used imported technology and paid little or no attention to innovation.36 The state created tar- iffs and multiple exchange rates to control imports. Social policy was not fo- cused on redistribution or poverty reduction; social protection programs were elitist, designed to keep the industrial working class and the small middle class happy and managed in a clientelistic fashion.37 The 1990s saw a partial reversal of the developmentalist model with privatization, liberalization, dismantling of the instruments of industrial pol- icy, and tentative steps toward poverty alleviation. But when it took office, the Lula government decided the state needed to resume a more active role in industrial development and to take more aggressive steps to relieve poverty and reduce inequality. The Lula administration recognized that markets were necessary but not sufficient for inclusive growth. The state could do more to promote growth with equity, and it started to act more selectively and aggressively in the econ- omy. This shift away from neoliberalism was as notable for what it did not do as for what it did. When Brazil began to develop new forms of state activism, it did not renationalize former state-owned enterprises, impose price controls, create a top-down development plan, discourage foreign investment, default on international obligations, engage in deficit spending, or close its markets to foreign goods. Rather, it sought to maintain and benefit from openness by ensuring the competiveness of the domestic industry. Efforts focused on qualities, benefiting the better organized and remunerated in the formal and public sectors disproportionately, this segmentation is now much less acute than it has been for decades, and perhaps since the creation of the country’s first social benefits many decades ago. In 2010 inequality in Brazil reached its lowest level since measurement started in 1960.” 36 During the import substitution period, Brazil copied technology from developed countries. This was often manifested in the form of factories owned by foreign companies that located R&D and innovation outside Brazil with no obligations to transfer technology. That meant that Brazilian industry had a very low level of capacity for innovation. See Ignácio José Go- dinho Delgado, “Desenvolvimento, empresariado e política industrial no Brasil,” in Estado, Empre- sariado e Desenvolvimento no Brasil: Novas Teorias, Novas Trajetórias, 115–141 (M. A. Leopoldi, W. P. Mancuso, & W. Iglecias ed., Editora de Cultura, 2010). 37 Arbix & Martin, supra note 4 observe that “over the course of several decades, the statist model shifted resources from consumption to investment, limiting real wages and social spending and directing social spending in clientelistic fashion toward more organized seg- ments of society with an eye toward political stability and control.” Toward a New Law and Development 295 constructing new forms of industrial policy that emphasized innovation and partnership with industry. At the same time, an emphasis was placed on social policy and redistribution and the combination of social policy with industrial growth strategies. The Rise and Shape of NSA What explains NSA and why did it take the shape that it did in Brazil? What impelled the Lula government to reintroduce industrial policy? Why did it choose to emphasize innovation, engage with the private sector, and structure the program in a more bottom-up fashion? Why did NSA link industrial and social policy and refocus social policy toward poverty alleviation and reduc- tion of inequality? No one would claim that Brazil’s new form of state activism was planned from the start or that a clear or completely stable model has emerged. No mas- ter plan ever emanated from a government think tank or planning ministry. These policies evolved in a piecemeal fashion and are still changing. The Bra- zilian government has been feeling the stones as it crosses the river—recalling Deng Xaoping’s phrase—not following an existing blueprint. However, look- ing back over a decade of experimentation and policy evolution, one can see several factors that explain the decision to resume an active role for the state as well as the forces that affected the form this role would take. This section considers three of these factors: political opportunity, structural impediments to growth, and international and domestic constraints. Taken together, they exemplify the profile of what Arbix and Martin call “new state activism with- out dominance.” A Political Moment When Lula was elected in 2002, growth had slowed and unemployment was very high. The effects of globalization and liberalization were being felt, and Brazilian companies were losing ground. It is not hard to understand why a government led by the Brazilian Workers Party (PT), predisposed to state activism, would want to increase the role of the state in the economy. But the PT was not alone—this view was shared by at least part of the wider business community. Business in general and many industrialists in particular wanted a more activist state and more voice in government policy.38 Although the PT was ideologically committed to state activism, the busi- ness community looked to the state as a force that could reignite growth. Dis- satisfied by the effects of liberalization in the 1990s, powerful industrial groups (including the Federation of Industries of São Paulo, or FIESP) involved them- selves in the electoral process in 2002 with the objective of “opening space for 38 Shunko Rojas suggests that changes in the leadership of the Federation of Industries in São Paulo led to FIESP support for an expanded state role well before the 2002 election. Private communication with the authors, Aug., 2012. The World Bank Legal Review296 developmentalist ideas.”39 Industry had played an important role in the old development state, so at least some industrialists were comfortable with an increased role for the state as long as they had a voice in state policy. Although Lula’s first administration took cautious steps toward state ac- tivism, interest in a stronger role for the state grew during Lula’s second term (2006–10). In this period, NSA gained appeal, importance, and political sup- port from industrialists, unions, intellectuals, and academics. Brazilian econo- mist Antonio Barros de Castro suggests that the Brazilian elite realized that it needed to “deal with China.”40 He notes that trade liberalization and the rise of China led much of Latin America to abandon industry and refocus on natural resources. Due to the large size and central importance of its industrial sector, Brazil could not and did not want to take this route. Despite the mod- ernization of Brazil’s industry that had made it globally competitive in some fields, once China came on the scene, Brazil was no longer as competitive. At the same time, Chinese demand for natural resources drove up the value of the real, thus further handicapping Brazilian industry by increasing the cost of exports and lowering the cost of imported manufactured goods. The situa- tion worsened, leading to a slowdown in 2005 and a public outcry about the economic situation that generated calls for more action by the state. The turning point came around 2006. As a result of a political scandal, Antonio Palocci, Lula’s finance minister, was replaced by Guido Mantega, a heterodox economist and academic closely linked to Lula. Palocci was also closely linked to the PT, had maintained an orthodox approach to economic policy, and was closer to the financial sector than to industry. His replacement opened a window of opportunity for the industrialists represented by insti- tutions such as the National Industry Confederation (CNI), FIESP, and the Economic Institute for Industrial Development (IEDI), a business think thank, to push for policies that would allow them to recover and protect industrial chains dismantled during the 1990s, foster international competitiveness, and channel more state funds into infrastructure investments. Business support for neoliberalism, never so robust, declined, and its acceptance of state activ- ism increased. Jackson De Toni suggests that “Brazilian industrialists partly conceded in their unconditional defense of a minimalist agenda for the state in exchange for a political economy that would maintain the inherited stability and defend them against external competition, but would also revive public investments in infrastructure.”41 39 They “correctly understood Lula’s election as a mandate for a pro-growth strategy,” says James Martin Cypher. Brazil’s Development Strategy: Maintaining the Industrial Base, Side Step- ping the Staples Trap? paper presented at at the 2012 Congress of the Latin American Studies Association, San Francisco, California, 8, 2012. 40 See de Castro, supra note 6. 41 Jackson de Toni, Estado e empresários na política industrial brasileira recente: Processos de coopera- ção e mudança institucional, paper presented at IPEA CODE (2011), available at http://www. ipea.gov.br/code/chamada2011/pdf/area10/area10-artigo2.pdf (accessed Jul. 21, 2012). http://www.ipea.gov.br/code/chamada2011/pdf/area10/area10-artigo2.pdf http://www.ipea.gov.br/code/chamada2011/pdf/area10/area10-artigo2.pdf Toward a New Law and Development 297 In this context, continues De Toni, the Lula government created some new “arenas” for public-private coordination (including councils such as CDES, CNDI, and the so-called competitiveness fora) and new agencies (such as ABDI) in an attempt to ensure legitimacy while controlling the increasing de- mands of industrial entrepreneurs. At the same time it launched the Growth Acceleration Program (PAC) in 2007. PAC was designed to restart investment using the strength of public companies like Petrobrás to lead the process. Another factor that helped cement political support for state activism was the global financial crisis. The pervasive and worldwide failure of markets, which were deeply affected by financial disorganization, epitomized the crisis of deregulated capitalism and legitimized the adoption of alternative policies. This gave more support for the expansion of industrial policy and the grow- ing role of BNDES. The government adopted a rhetoric that stressed that the crisis was an opportunity for Brazil to gain comparative advantages, requiring proactive state action. When the financial crisis broke out in 2008, the Brazilian economy was seriously challenged by the lack of credit. Like many institutions in the United States and Europe, Brazilian financial institutions halted the supply of credit. This led to more pressure by the industrial coalition for action by the Brazil- ian state. As a result, BNDES was heavily capitalized so that it could play a countercyclical role in the economy. BNDES sharply raised its disbursements, thus galvanizing a national industrial sector already suffering from reduced competitiveness and an unfavorable exchange rate and now also buffeted by credit stringency. In general, because of the worldwide crisis, the Brazilian government was able to become more active in shaping the trajectory of eco- nomic development. Structural Elements What problems did policy makers face and respond to as they shaped NSA? Three structural features were important: • Major market failures that impeded economic activity, including a low level of investment in infrastructure and a lack of innovation • Long-standing Brazilian social concerns • The international embeddedness of the Brazilian economy and its need to spur competitiveness Market Failures: Innovation, Infrastructure, Financial Sector, and Competitiveness Major domestic market failures forced policy makers to face the low level of innovation in Brazilian industry. By the early 2000s, they had recognized that Brazilian industry had slowed down and believed that markets alone could not restart the growth process and that state intervention was called for. The national economy had had its last impetus of vitality in the 1970s, during the The World Bank Legal Review298 apogee of “old” development state policies. In that decade, Brazil underwent a second industrial revolution, acquiring a diversified industrial base. But the economy started to stagnate due to external and internal factors, and begin- ning in the early 1980s, the economy endured a long period of stagnation, in which growth slowed and Brazil fell behind the rapidly growing Asian tigers. One external factor was changing global capitalist accumulation patterns and the consolidation of a knowledge-based economy,42 which made indus- trial innovation essential for economic competitiveness. The internal reasons included Brazil’s failure to reshape the political economy and the legal- institutional structure that underpinned the old developmentalism based on an alliance among the state, foreign capital, and national capital.43 The state provided infrastructure, organized key sectors of the economy through state- owned enterprises, generated savings that could be used for new investment, and created regulations and incentives to protect and promote the private sec- tor. Foreign capital helped develop local industry using technology that had been created and perfected in advanced markets; sometimes this included bringing in equipment that had become obsolete at home.44 One effect of this arrangement was that the Brazilian economy was largely insulated from in- ternational competition. This, in turn, reduced the pressure for national inno- vation and the development of new technology: Brazil was limited to buying externally-generated technology. This helped slow the pace of development. Suzigan and Villela conclude: It was necessary to change not only to correct these problems, but also because there was [an awareness] that the country had reached the zenith of a historical development process (which many errone- ously described simply as import substitution). Once an ample and diversified industrial basis [had been built], it was necessary to make it efficient and competitive. It was also necessary to incorporate sectors and industries representing new technologies, particularly informatics and telecommunications, and to develop innovation ability, a crucial element in competition.45 During this time, Asian countries, noticeably South Korea and Taiwan, were on a brisk developmental pace, giving rise to a new round of growth based on knowledge, innovation, and reduction of poverty and inequality. Brazil and its Latin American counterparts lost vitality. One indicator is the 42 See Michael J. Piore & Charles F. Sabel, The Second Industrial Divide: Possibilities for Prosperity (Basic Books, 1984); and David Harvey, The Condition of Postmodernity: An Enquiry into the Origins of Cultural Change (Wiley-Blackwell, 1991). 43 Peter Evans, Embedded Autonomy: States and Industrial Transformation (Princeton U. Press, 1995). 44 See Lincoln Gordon & Englebert L. Grommers, United States Manufacturing Investment in Brazil: The Impact of Brazilian Government Policies 1946–1960 (Division of Research, Graduate School of Business Administration, Harvard U., 1962). 45 Suzigan & Villela, supra note 23. Toward a New Law and Development 299 relative success in patenting: Asians far surpassed Latin Americans in patents issued in the United States. Brazilian policy makers took steps to increase the rate of innovation in in- dustrial activity. Modest efforts to stimulate innovation began as early as 1999, but with the reintroduction of industrial policy in 2004, substantial resources were devoted to improving the overall climate for innovation; supporting re- structuring in targeted industries; and fostering the development of new areas of specialization considered relevant and potentially able to consolidate key industrial chains. Another structural barrier to growth was the low level of investment in infrastructure. The private sector was unwilling to invest in needed infra- structure expansion, and the state had not compensated for this deficiency. Although Brazil has one of the highest tax burdens in the world, public sector investment was relatively low, even by Latin American standards.46 The private financial sector played a large role in the structural economic failure in Brazil. Although it had grown in size and importance, the private sector still funded industrial expansion in only limited amounts. State banks, which date to the developmental period, filled the gap. When the Lula gov- ernment decided to implement a broader industrial policy, it looked to the state banks, especially to BNDES, to prove the capital and expertise needed for growth, innovation, and competiveness and to buffer the effects of the fi- nancial crises.47 Unlike other developing countries, Brazil did not dismantle its development bank in the 1990s, so that institution was available when the government decided to intervene more actively in the economy. Today, the state bank is the main source of long-term financing in Brazil and a key actor in the conception and implementation of industrial policy. The fourth structural problem that affected the emergence of state activ- ism is the side effect of the Plano Real. Undeniably, the Plano Real achieved its goal of ending runaway inflation. Since 1994, when the plan was im- plemented, inflation has been kept in check at around 5 percent per year. The problem, however, is that this plan is anchored in the interplay of two 46 José Roberto Rodrigues Afonso, Erika Amorim Araújo, & Geraldo Biasoto Júnior, Fiscal Space and Public Sector Investments in Infrastructure: A Brazilian Case-Study, 1141 Textos Para Dis- cussão IPEA (2005). Commenting on the infrastructure deficit in Brazil, Daniel Perrotti notes: “Although several factors were involved (such as high macroeconomic volatility, the lack of comprehensive policies and regulatory and financing issues), the effects of these physi- cal constraints are obvious and seriously threaten future development.” See The Economic Infrastructure Gap in Latin America and the Caribbean, 293 FAL Bulletin (2011), available at http://www.cepal.org/usi/noticias/bolfall/6/42926/FAL-293-WEB-ENG-2.pdf (accessed Jul., 20, 2012). 47 BNDES and the other major state banks have access to public (pension and treasury) funds, so their cost of capital is well below that of the private sector. BNDES also makes profits and raises funds in the capital market, besides offering substantial expertise; the bank has been financing the Brazilian industrial sector for 50 years and has developed detailed knowledge of many important sectors and close ties to industry that add to its advantages over the pri- vate sector. http://www.cepal.org/usi/noticias/bolfall/6/42926/FAL-293-WEB-ENG-2.pdf The World Bank Legal Review300 macroeconomic variables: interest rate and exchange rate. Whereas the in- terest rate is the main control against inflation, the exchange rate is directly influenced by the interest rate: if the interest rate is high, it attracts foreign investment, which results in an appreciation of the exchange rate. This has two direct consequences. First, the regulation of inflation by management of the interest rate creates side effects in the financial markets, inasmuch as appreciation of the value of the currency encourages investors—including foreign investors—to buy government bonds. This means that less money is available for the private sector. Second, the resulting appreciation of the ex- change rate affects domestic industry because it makes imports cheaper and exports less competitive. This situation put pressure on policy makers: in- dustry pressed for solutions that would lower the cost of finance and guard against deindustrialization. Industrial policy seemed like a way to handle both concerns. Social Concerns Social concerns shaped the development of NSA in Brazil, in particular four issues: poverty, social inequality, unemployment; and the tendency of wages to lag behind productivity. In 1981, 31 percent of the Brazilian population was living on less than US$2 per day. Other social indicators were negative: child mortality was high, life expectancy at birth was only 63 years, illiteracy was widespread, and many people had no regular access to sanitation and potable water.48 Econom- ic inequality was extreme. Brazil has been profoundly unequal and unjust for a long time: in 1990, the Gini coefficient was 0.6091. The degree of inequality is further aggravated when considering race and gender. Unemployment was also high: the rate of unemployment reached 10 percent in the early 1990s, and from the 1980s to 2000, unemployment was a crucial political issue.49 Educa- tion was also a problem: the education system did not produce the number of skilled people needed by a growing and competitive economy. Industrial poli- cies designed to spur technological upgrading were hampered by the lack of adequate human resources; people did not have the skills needed in a chang- ing labor market. The government recognized the need for job creation and skills upgrading in connection with social and welfare initiatives. Wage lag is another social issue in Brazil. Because of the large rural popula- tion in most Latin American countries including Brazil, a huge pool of under- employed workers depresses wage levels.50 As a result, domestic demand does not grow as fast as domestic production, thus hindering growth of the 48 Data in this section is taken from Mauricio Font & Laura Randall, The Brazilian State: Debate and Agenda (Lexington Books, 2011). 49 Id. Some observers put the effective rate as high as 20 percent. 50 This is what W. Arthur Lewis called development with “unlimited supplies of labor.” Toward a New Law and Development 301 domestic market. Economists stress the need for government action to offset this with an income policy that will bring wages up to optimal levels.51 International Embeddedness and the Need to Spur Competitiveness A third structural feature affecting the emergence of NSA was Lula’s decision to liberalize the economy and maintain openness. Although export promo- tion had been a development target since the 1960s, domestic industrialization dominated the governmental agenda until the 1990s. This situation changed with globalization and liberalization. In the 1990s, Brazil opened itself to in- ternational competition and began to actively pursue export markets, forcing the state to pay more attention to competitiveness. When Lula’s government took office, one of its first moves was to em- phasize the need for state action to encourage the solutions needed to main- tain competitiveness. This decision, brought about by the commitment to open economy policies, explains both the revival of industrial policy and the government emphasis on innovation. From PITCE through Brasil Maior, policies have focused on boosting the international competitiveness of Bra- zilian companies, including BNDES’s support for the internationalization of Brazil’s most competitive industries and various mechanisms to subsidize exports. Although the government has recognized the importance of com- petiveness and that maintaining openness to foreign goods is necessary to preserve competiveness, it has also taken measures to provide protection for domestic industries. Structural Elements: Conditioning Factors The stage was set for the government, led by the Brazilian Workers Party, to increase the role of the state in the economy. But why did Brazil’s role as a development state take the shape that it did? Why did Brazil opt for an in- novation-focused and collaborative public-private form of industrial policy rather than, say, renationalization as did Venezuela, Argentina, Ecuador, and Bolivia? Why was Brazil supportive of foreign investment in most sectors? This section discusses factors that influenced the choices Brazil has made in its search to help the economy regain dynamism and promote inclusive growth. Among these factors, four are especially important: • Constitutional considerations • The strength and scope of the private sector • International economic law and policy • Global financial markets 51 Bresser-Pereira, supra note 4 at 193. The World Bank Legal Review302 Constitutional Considerations The 1988 constitution influenced the choice of strategies and measures by mak- ing direct state control of industry both more expensive and less important than in the past. The new constitution protected property rights and regula- tory commitments, thus making renationalization of privatized industries an expensive proposition. It reduced the possibilities for corruption and for pri- vate capture of state power, thus increasing the government’s capacity to steer the private sector and provide control and accountability mechanisms for the public sector. This made state ownership seem less necessary. Finally, by creat- ing an open and democratic political structure, the constitution enhanced the power and participation of civil society, including industry, vis-à-vis the state. The Private Sector The size, complexity, and sophistication of the private sector in Brazil influ- enced the path of collaborative innovation-oriented industrial policy. The Bra- zilian economy includes many well-developed sectors and a growing capital market. Many firms are either at the global competitive frontier or close to it. Others have incipient capabilities. Many sectors accept the need for restructur- ing and continuous improvement. Many firms have the kind of deep knowl- edge essential for effective innovation even though they may not be able fully to utilize this knowledge without public incentives and support. It must have seemed much easier to create incentives for these firms to innovate and provide support for new private start-ups than to try to replace them with state-owned enterprises. At the same time, the size and scope of the private sector meant that once democracy was restored, the private sec- tor gained an important voice in public affairs. The private sector was eager to support an expanded role for the state as long as this support was offered in collaboration with industry and was appropriate to resume growth. Thus, Cypher notes: given the many endemic macroeconomic problems that had made the 1990s a period of slow growth in spite of the restructuring of industry, powerful industrial groups (including the Federation of Industries of São Paulo) involved themselves in the electoral process in 2002 with the objective of “opening space for developmentalist ideas” (Delgado 2010: 125) . . . the business federations—the organi- zations representing the interests of Brazil’s vast and diversified in- dustrial base—correctly understood Lula’s election as a mandate for a pro-growth strategy and as an indication that a structural change would occur opening-up channels of direct intermediation between the industrial sector and the new administration. . . . In short, there was a consensus between the PT and important fractions of indus- trial capital to reverse “the loss of the centrality of the State as an agent of accumulation.”52 52 See supra note 39. Toward a New Law and Development 303 International Economic Law and Policy World Trade Organization (WTO) law places restrictions on policies like ex- port subsidies and weak enforcement of intellectual property that had been used by the East Asian states, so Brazil had to work around these restraints or find ways to defend them. The Lula administration did a little of both by de- fending some heterodox policies and modifying others.53 Because it never rati- fied the Bilateral Investment Treaties (BITs) signed in the 1990s, Brazil did not encounter similar restrictions in international investment law. Nonetheless, because the government recognized that foreign investment was important for its innovation strategy and sought to encourage its own firms to invest in foreign markets, it followed many of the principles of the investment regime. Similarly, while Brazil’s export surpluses and growing reserves have made it less dependent on international financial institutions, Brazil has been influ- enced by the World Bank and other international financial institutions that promote market solutions but accept industrial policy as long as it respects comparative advantage and focuses on innovation. Global Financial Markets The Lula government decided to rely on foreign investment to help it reach and maintain international competiveness. It realized that classic protection- ism would threaten the availability of such investment, while an innovation- oriented and collaborative industrial policy offering selected benefits and in- centives to both foreign and domestic firms would be acceptable to investors. Other Influences on the Emergence of NSA Several other factors help explain the profile of Brazil’s NSA, including the in- creased professionalism of the state apparatus and bureaucracy, which made it possible to carry out industrial policy, and the rise of alternative economic theories that legitimized state activism. The macroinstitutional arrangement provided by the 1988 constitution contributed to upgrading state capacity and played an important role in NSA. In the past few decades, the Brazilian state has enhanced internal coordination, increased public-private collaboration, and learned how to better define policy mandates. Thus, NSA is partly the re- sult of institutional learning, through which the Brazilian state progressively acquired greater administrative capacity and the expertise needed to imple- ment complex and ambitious development policies. Until recently, the vast majority of public employees was appointed po- litically, weakening the public service ethos necessary to build a professional bureaucracy staffed by people with technical expertise who can administer 53 See Alvaro Santos, Carving out Policy Autonomy for Developing Countries in the World Trade Organization: The Experience of Brazil and Mexico; and Michelle Ratton Sanchez Badin, Devel- opmental Responses to the International Trade Legal Game: Cases of Intellectual Property and Export Credit Law Reforms in Brazil, in Trubek et al., supra note 1. The World Bank Legal Review304 policies rationally and efficiently. There were some islands of excellence in public administration: some key institutions of developmental coordina- tion, such as BNDES, Petrobrás, Embraer, Embrapa, IPEA, and the Central Bank, were professionalized. But these cases were in stark contrast to the rest of public administration, which compromised state capability. This lack of professionalism changed with the 1988 constitution, which mandated the re- cruitment of public employees through public and official exams (concursos públicos). As a result, there has been a substantial increase in the percentage of public employees selected meritocratically. The constitution also regulates the ceiling of earnings, determining that the maximum wage should be no higher than that one received by members of the Supreme Court (Supremo Tribunal Federal). This rule was designed to limit public expense and curb discretionary distortions in the level of salaries. Although both meritocratic recruitment and wage policy face problems of en- forcement, they represent an improvement in terms of governmental quality. When the Lula administration began to expand the state’s role, it could count on a more professional workforce in government. Other measures helped enhance state capacity, making it easier to carry out the direction called for by NSA. The constitutional framework estab- lished in 1988 gave rise to policy initiatives designed to “implement rights” and “modernize” the state. New ministries were created, several others were reorganized, subministerial entities were added, and councils and commit- tees were formed to increase participation by business and labor. In addition, BNDES has played an increasingly important role in industrial policy. Changes in the world of ideas also facilitated NSA. With the turn to a more robust role for the state in the economy, and its particular profile in Bra- zil, there have been corresponding changes on the intellectual scene. Inter- nationally, more attention is paid to the positive role industrial policy might play, and the World Bank has endorsed certain types of industrial policy.54 Similar developments are occurring within Brazil as Brazilian economists seek to explain and guide the evolving new configuration. Brazil has also attracted the attention of theorists around the world who hope to create a new political economy of development.55 The academic focus has resulted in analytical tools and offers intellectual justifications that can help sustain policy experimentation. Some observers have labeled the emerging set of ideas “new developmentalism.” James Cypher describes this approach: On the one hand, New Developmentalism [rejects] prevailing ideas of neoclassical economics regarding a passive reliance on an export- 54 Justin Yifu Lin, New Structural Economics: A Framework for Rethinking Development (World Bank, 2012), available at http://siteresources.worldbank.org/INTVIETNAM/Resources/ Jtin.pdf. 55 For a detailed discussion of Brazil and new developmentalism, see David M. Trubek, Law, State, and the New Developmentalism: An Introduction, in Trubek et al., supra note 1. http://siteresources.worldbank.org/INTVIETNAM/Resources/Jtin.pdf http://siteresources.worldbank.org/INTVIETNAM/Resources/Jtin.pdf Toward a New Law and Development 305 led, resource-based economy [and agrees with]. . . . the original de- velopmentalist economists such as Rosenstein-Rodan, Hirschman, and Nurkse, and their emphasis on the centrality of a developmen- talist state. . . . On the other hand, New Developmentalism stresses a “growth with equity” approach along with an emphasis on indus- trial policy, highlighting public, growth-supporting, infrastructure spending, and a “neoschumpeterian” emphasis on building a na- tional innovation system through deep public-private cooperative programs that will drive investment expenditures toward produc- tivity-enhancing science and technology applications throughout the national industrial base of the economy.56 In Brazil, after the relative theoretical hegemony of liberal ideas associ- ated with the Washington Consensus in the 1990s, a burgeoning literature has lent support for NSA. This can be seen in two different fields: economics (both macroeconomics and microeconomics) and political science. In econom- ics, an important contribution has been research on the exchange rate and its effect on industrialization. According to the argument developed by Bresser- Pereira, there has been appreciation of the value of the real, leading to a “Dutch disease” effect that promotes deindustrialization.57 Due to the floods of dollars that have been reaching the Brazilian economy, the currency has be- come overvalued, with a negative effect on national industry. By showing that free market policies can lead to these negative effects, Bresser-Pereira and his colleagues created a rationale for an aggressive industrial policy. This criticism was accompanied by microeconomic studies that challenge the market-orient- ed model. These studies include sectorial and market analyses and document specific and pervasive market failures that require active industrial policies.58 In addition, microeconomists and political scientists have been providing inputs to social policy. Studies have demonstrated how economic inequality itself is a problem, detaching this problem from poverty. This sort of consid- eration has given impulse to the formulation of two different sets of social measures: poverty alleviation measures and instruments intended to reduce economic inequality more generally. 56 Cypher, supra note 39, comments that “As yet, New Developmentalism has not been rigor- ously defined. Some find that trial and error rather than the adoption of a coherent ‘model’ such as ‘new-developmentalism’ better describes the current conjuncture,” citing Arbix & Martin, supra note 4. 57 The “Dutch disease” refers to the effect of a commodities boom on industry. Increased de- mand for commodities leads to appreciation of the currency, which makes industrial exports less competitive. This occurred in the Netherlands with the discovery of natural gas. See Luiz Carlos Bresser-Pereira, The Dutch Disease and Its Neutralization: A Ricardian Approach, 28 Brazilian J. of Pol. Eco. 47 –71 (2008). 58 Two issues have been highlighted: failures in the market for innovation and gaps in the industrial chain. Studies conducted by Arbix & Pacheco and the Institute for Economic Ap- plied Research show the need for innovation policies, while Erber, Cassiolato, & Kupfer highlight gaps in supply chains that require government action. The World Bank Legal Review306 Challenge for Law What does the emergence of NSA mean for law, and vice versa? As the role of the state in the economy and social protection changes, there will be corre- sponding changes in law. And it seems possible that law will shape and chan- nel the path for policy innovation, as well as providing room for adaptation. This section outlines some general considerations about NSA’s challenges for law. Although it is easy to say that law and NSA must in some way be mutu- ally constitutive, it is another matter to say how NSA affects law and vice versa. Part of the problem derives from the complexity of the situation, and part from the paucity of empirical studies. Although abstract models of po- litical economy such as neoliberalism and new developmentalism suggest clear delineations, in the real world, policies are a mix of the old and the new, layered on top of one another, and sometimes contradictory. This complex- ity and contradiction at the policy level carries over into the legal domain: key legal variables are difficult to define and causalities involving changes in the law and in policy outcomes are blurred. As a result, studies on rela- tionships between the law and development policy present methodological challenges. This section focuses on methods for understanding these relationships, outlines some functionalities that NSA seems to demand, and provides a few examples of how law has responded to these functional needs. New Roles, New Frameworks of Analysis, New Functionalities NSA will generate pressures for new laws and new roles for law. Much will be straightforward: statutes will change, procedures will be altered. This has been occurring in Brazil for years. Laws created ABDI, MDS, Cadastro Unico, and other institutions that are central to Brazil’s NSA. Laws aiming at specific goals such as innovation and competiveness are also important. Although recognizing the importance of these legal changes, this section focuses on “new functionalities”—roles for law that have not been as important (or did not exist in Brazil) in the past and take on new importance with the emer- gence of NSA. Three sources were used to identify new functionalities and legal respons- es: research done by the project on Law and the New Developmental State (LANDS), of which this study is a part;59 other research on law and develop- 59 LANDS, the Project on Law and the New Developmental State, is coordinated by the Global Legal Studies Center at the University of Wisconsin, Madison with assistance from CEBRAP (the Brazilian Center for Analysis and Planning), and Los Andes University. Funding for LANDS was provided by the University of Wisconsin School of Law, the University of Wis- consin’s Center for World Affairs and the Global Economy (WAGE), and the Ford Foundation. Toward a New Law and Development 307 ment polices conducted in Brazil;60 and “reverse engineering.”61 Reverse engi- neering means starting with policies and programs, describing the functions associated with them, and seeing if law has contributed, or could contribute, to those functions. For NSA to be successful and new development policies to work, the government must maintain flexibility, orchestrate the relations among public actors and between them and the private sector, create conditions that will maximize synergy between actors, and preserve legitimacy. These functional needs point to new roles for law: if one isolates the role law can play in these new functionalities, one can identify four roles the legal system could play in NSA in Brazil: safeguard flexibility, stimulate orchestration, frame synergy, and ensure legitimacy. Safeguard flexibility means to use legal norms to allow room for experimen- tation, to promote innovation, and to facilitate feedback from experiments to policy. NSA demands legal regimes that permit learning by doing and that encourage path correction. Different from import substitution and neoliberal- ism, NSA requires the assurance of some degree of flexibility and learning to implement initiatives that in most cases do not resemble preexisting recipes or strategies; this is one reason why NSA employs “new governance” tools.62 Stimulate orchestration means to use law to structure state activities for ef- fective industrial and social policy. This means facilitating coordination and articulation within the state—both horizontally (that is, between entities that belong to the same bureaucratic state level) and vertically (that is, between entities that are subject to hierarchies or belong to different state levels). 60 Diogo R. Coutinho & Paulo T. L. Mattos, “Law and the New Developmental State: Brazil Pilot Project,” paper presented at the workshop “Law and the New Developmental State: Lat- in America and Beyond,” Global Legal Studies Center—Center for World Affairs and the Global Economy (WAGE), University of Wisconsin, Madison (2008); Fabiani, supra note 16; Roberto Pires, Promoting Sustainable Compliance: Styles of Labour Inspection and Compliance Outcomes in Brazil, 147 Intl. Lab. Rev. 199–229 (2008); Mariana Mota Prado & Ana Carolina da Matta Chasin, How Innovative Was the Poupatempo Experience in Brazil? Institutional Bypass as a New Form of Institutional Change, 1 Brazilian Pol. Sci. Rev. (2011); Mario Gomes Schapiro, Development Bank, Law and Innovation Financing in a New Brazilian Economy, 1045 L. & Dev. Rev.; Gregory C. Shaffer, Michelle Ratton Sanchez, & Barbara Rosenberg, The Trials of Win- ning at the WTO: What Lies Behind Brazil’s Success, 41 Cornell Intl. J. 2 (2008). 61 The idea of reverse engineering appears in David Kennedy, The Rule of Law, Political Choices, and Development Common Sense, in The New Law and Development—A Critical Appraisal (David Trubek & Alvaro Santos ed., Cambridge U. Press 2006), in the context of a discussion of the postwar consensus (1945–70). Kennedy reckons that although there was a clear demand for instrumental law during this period, the legal theory was implicit. In order to reveal it, he proposes, “We need to reverse engineer the legal theory of mainstream development profes- sionals from their economic and political projects, and from the attitudes toward law they manifested in managing developing policies within national administration. A great deal of law was required to translate the leading economic theories of development economic policy.” 62 For a thorough account of new governance and its legal functions and tools, see Orly Lobel, The Renew Deal: The Fall of Regulation and the Rise of Governance in Contemporary Legal Thought, 89 Minn. L. Rev. (2004). The World Bank Legal Review308 Orchestration can consist of norms and procedures that assign institutional tasks and foster cooperative (rather than competitive) governance regimes, including rules that encourage government to work with the private sector. Also, it can mean supporting policy networks that share tasks and interact in a complementary way to implement policies; this can include defining pol- icy hubs. Finally, orchestration can mean using norms that harmonize new policies with preexisting ones to ensure coherence. Norms and processes playing these roles are crucial in NSA because it relies on the integration of different fields. Frame synergy involves using the law to frame public-private partnerships and ensure that they are more effective than purely public or private solu- tions. Such modalities include collaborative governance regimes that create incentives for public-private cooperation (through incentive alignment and/ or the use of private contracts by public entities), risk sharing,63 and hybrid instances in which public and private players regularly meet to interact and exchange opinions on regulatory and contractual instruments that bring pri- vate expertise and public financial capacity together. Ensure legitimacy means to keep government transparent and ensure ad- equate participation. NSA requires a regime in which it is easy for new ideas to percolate upward and be widely shared. This makes older authoritarian mod- els obsolete and increases the importance of democracy. Legal regimes must ensure accountability, transparency, and participation in development policies, which requires norms for disclosure, frameworks for participation, methods to hold policy makers accountable for results, and ways to avoid industry capture of government at the same time public-private dialogue is fostered. Developments in industrial and social policy illustrate how Brazil is deal- ing with these new needs and functionalities. Flexibility and Synergy in Industrial Policy The industrial policy promoted by NSA in Brazil is as much process as policy. It is part of a joint public-private discovery process, a collaboration through which partners experiment with different trajectories to identify products and processes that are optimal for individual firms and sectors as a whole. Ef- forts to encourage innovation through a full-scale partnership with the private sector move the state into new territory. For example, instead of traditional arms-length lending with well-defined goals set in advance, internationaliza- tion strategies for Brazilian companies and innovation financing call for sub- stantial flexibility, risk sharing, and alliances—this requires legal innovation. One area in which this is occurring is BNDES’s program to foster inno- vation that replaced its traditional form of fixed obligation loan agreements with a variety of flexible devices that support collaboration and experimen- tation. The tools developed for this purpose represent a break in BNDES’s 63 Coutinho & Mattos, supra note 60. Toward a New Law and Development 309 legal pattern: the bank relies on flexible legal structures that, formally or in- formally, support a financial relationship that permits changes of trajectory and adaptation of plans. These legal tools include partnerships with techno- logical institutes and grants to promote the development of new products; relational loan contracts that include nonbinding performance criteria, staged disbursements, and constant BNDES monitoring through shared governance mechanisms; equity investments coupled with shared governance established through shareholder agreements that give BNDES a seat on the board and that subject certain corporate decisions to its approval; and arrangements by which BNDES participates on the investment committee of venture capital funds that it assists.64 Other new legal mechanisms connected with industrial policy include risk sharing with the private sector, soft law, and special public-private part- nerships. Risk-sharing agreements are designed to encourage private inves- tors to increase investments in technological research and innovation, expand industry capacity and exports, and acquire assets abroad in order to exploit comparative advantage in sectors where Brazil is a global leader. Soft law has also been used to induce investment. For example, governmental letters of intent communicate public investment strategies and serve as signals for the private sector, inducing private investment decisions. Other tools that create incentives for private companies to innovate include public-private partner- ship contracts, cooperation agreements between government and research centers, and flexible private law contracts (credit contracts, shareholder and investors agreements) between government and corporations. Orchestration and Decentralization in Social Policy Brazil has sought to strengthen its welfare state through cooperation among the several levels of government in the federation. It also brings together dif- ferent types of social policies to deal with major problems. This requires a continuous orchestration of different levels and types of policies (universal and targeted, federal and local, contributive and noncontributive). Thus, the government has found new uses for old administrative law tools and created new instruments. This strategy can be seen in BFP, which uses a registry for all social programs (Cadastro Único) and a decentralized management index (IGD) to coordinate the work of several ministries, local administrators, and other public actors and to encourage policy innovation. BFP uses conditionali- ties—obligations of recipients for child education and health—that it enforces through revisable regulatory rules such as ordinances. It employs the Cadas- tro Único to gather data and reduce asymmetric information with the purpose of expanding education and health coverage. It also adopted a carrot-based 64 Mario Schapiro, Rediscovering the Developmental Path? Development Bank, Law and Innovation Financing in the Brazilian Economy, in Trubek et al., supra note 1. Although the bank’s inno- vation funding clearly represents a new form of state activism and new approaches to law, Schapiro emphasizes that the program represents a tiny portion of the bank’s total portfolio, and it is unclear whether this segment of the program will expand in the future. The World Bank Legal Review310 federal arrangement through the use of financial incentives such as IGD to get municipalities to gather data on very poor families. In addition, IGD aims to encourage Brazilian cities to deliver effective performance, employing funds to reward those who provide dependable and quality information, maintaining updated data in the Cadastro Único, and providing information on the effect of the health and education conditionali- ties. BFP uses contractual arrangements with cities to ensure that they set up local agencies of social control and participation. These agencies receive IGD funding to support the BFP management and develop activities with recipi- ent households, including managing conditionalities and benefits, monitoring recipient households, registering new households, updating and reviewing data, implementing complementary programs for basic adult literacy, provid- ing occupational training, creating jobs and income, stimulating regional de- velopment, and strengthening BFP’s social control. This system has led to a more collaborative (rather than imposed) and flex- ible (rather than based on rigid rules and sanctions) relationship between the federal and local levels.65 Such an articulation fosters decentralization (with federal guidance, steering, and expertise) and is the result of a broader picture in which, although universal programs remain central, “targeting within uni- versalism” has been fostering development outcomes. Experimentation and Synergy in Labor Law In a study of new approaches to the enforcement of labor laws in Brazil, Rober- to Pires shows that labor inspectors using flexible and reflexive experimental- ist governance approaches had more success than their peers who employed more traditional management tools.66 The study compares two different styles of enforcement: one, drawn from the theories of the new public management stresses, specific targets and quotas67; the other, which draws more on the ex- perimentalist governance literature, stresses public-private cooperation, dia- logue, exploration of options for compliance, careful analysis of the causes of violations, and revision of goals and standards as mutual learning progresses. Pires shows that through a system of hybrid governance that employs exper- imentalist methods while keeping sanctions in the background, health and safety inspectors in Pernambuco are able to significantly reduce the incidence of industrial accidents. The key to this success, Pires suggests, is creating institutions that allow interaction among government, business, and labor; encourage the search for 65 Diogo R. Coutinho, Decentralization and Coordination in Social Law and Policy: The Bolsa Familia Program, in Trubek et al., supra note 1. 66 Roberto Pires, Promoting Sustainable Compliance: Styles of Labour Inspection and Compliance Outcomes in Brazil 147(2–3) Intl. Lab. Rev. 199–229 (Jun./Sep. 2008). 67 New public management refers to the idea, and consequent policy prescriptions, that market- oriented management of the public sector will lead to greater cost efficiency for govern- ments. It gained its momentum during the 1990s. Toward a New Law and Development 311 ways companies could revise their business plans to comply with the law and still prosper; and facilitate experimentation with new technologies that might reduce risks of accidents at low cost. He notes that because of the success of these methods, the experimentalist model has been scaled up to the federal level. Although Pires does not relate his study and the growth of experimen- talism in governance directly to the new political economy of development or how the Brazilian government is redefining its role in that development, the affinity between the development literature and changes in public administra- tion seems clear. Building Legal Capacity for Development: Trade Law In addition to adapting law to deal with functionalities demanded by NSA, Brazil has built the legal capacity needed to shield the new industrial and so- cial policies from restrictions that might be imposed by international law and policy. Built into NSA are policies that challenge some orthodox prescriptions backed by international economic law, including restraints on export subsi- dies and stricter protection of intellectual property. The clearest example of this kind of legal response is in the field of trade law.68 When it initially joined the WTO in 1995, Brazil accepted the full package of WTO agreements without first determining to what extent they might clash with domestic policies and priorities. But as neoliberal enthusiasm waned, successive administrations protected domestic policy space by challenging restrictive interpretations of global trade rules. This growing willingness to challenge WTO-based restrictions is a result of changes in development policy and in the way trade policy is formulated in Brazil. As the state began to play a more robust role in the promotion of economic growth and social protec- tion, trade policy making became more closely integrated with overall devel- opment policy, and Brazil invested in the legal and related skills needed for success in trade disputes. At the same time, the arena for discussion of trade policy expanded as more government agencies began to participate and the private sector and a flourishing civil society movement entered the debate. As a result, Brazil has been able to use trade law as a shield for policy innovation. In the case of intellectual property, Brazil was able to carve out space within the regime for the Agreement on Trade-Related Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights (TRIPS) that allowed it to negotiate better prices for antiviral drugs. Although initially it seemed that TRIPS would preclude this kind of ac- tion, a number of changes in law, politics, and government organization at the domestic level, as well as action in the international arena, strengthened the Brazilian government’s capacity to shape domestic health policy in the face of international constraints. The judiciary entered the arena to enforce a 68 See Alvaro Santos, Carving out Policy Autonomy for Developing Countries in the World Trade Organization: The Experience of Brazil and Mexico; and Michelle Ratton Sanchez Badin, Devel- opmental Responses to the International Trade Legal Game: Cases of Intellectual Property and Export Credit Law Reforms in Brazil, in Trubek et al., supra note 1. The World Bank Legal Review312 constitutional right to health, administrative changes were made that opened trade policy discussions to a range of interests, and the legislature was mobilized. Specific legal changes at the domestic level included reforms of the legal system in order to eliminate TRIPS-plus provisions; authorization for use of flexibilities such as compulsory licenses; the approval of new mechanisms im- plicitly authorized by the international system that favor access to technology; and the creation of new government institutions that could serve as counter- vailing powers to industry interests in the patent approval process. Brazil and other developing countries carried on a campaign at the international level that led the WTO and the World Intellectual Property Organization (WIPO) to take a more supportive stance toward the use of policy in this field. Brazil has been able to legally protect domestic trade policy from WTO restrictions. As part of its new industrial policy, Brazil sought to build Embraer into a national champion and facilitate efforts to develop market share in the global regional jet market. Government financing is an essential part of any deal for aircraft manufacturers, and Embraer had been hampered by the high cost of finance available to Brazilian companies. The government decided to provide a subsidy to the institutions that provided finance for Embraer sales. Canada’s Bombardier challenged this practice as a violation of the WTO sub- sidies code. After a long and drawn out litigation, Brazil was forced to make changes in its subsidies. But through a partially successful campaign that drew on the growing capacity of government and industry working together in the trade law field, Brazil was able to preserve part of the subsidy program and shift the issue of aircraft financing terms into the Organization for Economic Cooperation and Development (OECD). By moving the issue to the OECD, Brazil gained a voice in the main forum affecting global rules for aircraft fi- nance. This meant it has a say in the terms affecting its competitors and thus more bargaining leverage in the continuing dispute with Bombardier. Conclusion: Assessing the Brazilian Experience in Development Policy and Law The Brazilian foray into NSA is a work in progress. Policies are altered as domestic and international conditions change. Industrial policy seems to be working and is helping the country both weather the storms from the global financial crisis and resume economic dynamism. World markets have accept- ed this trend, and foreign investment has soared. Significant gains have been made in poverty alleviation and the reduction of economic inequality. Yet questions remain. Is a coherent model of a new development state emerging, and is Brazil’s new state activism likely to become consolidated? Does the government have the capacity to manage and implement the ambi- tious set of processes and policies that have been put in place? Can Brazilian institutions develop and sustain the new roles demanded by NSA? Finally, is the Brazilian experience unique to that country, or can it be replicated? Toward a New Law and Development 313 A New Development State? Although the current situation in Brazil is described here as NSA, a discussion of a “new Brazil model” in the sense of a coherent and stable configuration of state, law, and political economy would be premature. Brazil is experimenting with a variety of new policies and procedures. Many of them have yet to stand the test of time. But the trends show continuous movement toward a set of policies that could cohere into a sustainable model. A new form of industrial policy stressing state assistance for innovation and competitiveness in the pri- vate and public sectors is in place and has been combined with a robust social policy. The commitment to NSA has lasted for more than a decade, through two presidential elections. President Dilma Rousseff has deepened the gov- ernment’s commitment to the new industrial and social policies. Does Brazil Have the Capacity to Manage and Implement the New Policies? NSA places great demands on the state, which must be able to assist the private sector without stifling it. It must make choices among sectors, industries, and firms in the public interest. Complicated decisions involving massive sums of money require both technical expertise and distance from special interests. Through a series of reforms, the Brazilian state bureaucracy is more profes- sional today than it was in the past. But this is not true everywhere, and in many areas inefficiency, bureaucratic rigidity, or both, persist. Finally, the risk of corruption and capture is always present. Some measures have been taken to limit corruption; although new anticorruption laws and agencies have been created, corruption remains a problem in Brazil as elsewhere. Can the Brazilian Legal System Meet the Needs of NSA? Brazilian law can contribute to the operation of the new policies and proce- dures under NSA. In at least a few cases and a few areas, new legal tools are being created and old ones are being put to new use. The legal system has the capacity for innovation that new developmentalism demands. But it is not clear that this is happening—or will happen—in all the areas where change is needed. The cases that have been studied suggest it is possible, but they are too limited to warrant a conclusion. For that to happen, many rigidities and obstacles in the Brazil legal system must be overcome. Is the Brazilian Experience Unique, or Can It Be Replicated? There is no question that other nations can learn from the Brazilian experi- ence in development policy. The approach to industrial policy that assists the private sector and fosters structural changes needed for competiveness can be followed in other countries. The potential for using a state development bank as an engine of innovation and growth also provides lessons that can be replicated. Brazil’s successful merger of industrial policy and social policy is worth further study. The same can be said for the Brazilian experience in law and development. To the extent that countries adopt aspects of NSA, they will The World Bank Legal Review314 need to adapt their legal system to new functionalities and can learn from the way Brazil has developed legal institutions that address these needs. That does not mean, however, that the Brazilian experience has resulted in a template that can be followed by everyone, everywhere. The account pre- sented in this chapter has stressed the contextual features that explain Brazil’s turn to NSA, such as a large, well-developed industrial sector, advanced re- search centers, a huge domestic market, a democratic constitution, a profes- sionalized bureaucracy in key agencies, a long history of state involvement in the economy, and some transformative capacity in legal institutions. Because the development of NSA in Brazil is based on these contextual features, NSA in the Brazilian form will not be easily replicated in countries that lack any or all of these features. The Role of the Public Ministry in the Defense of the Environment Hydrogeographical Regions and Attitudes for Coping with Socioenvironmental Conflicts Luciano Badini and Luciano aLvarenga The Brazilian Constitution of 1988, the first constitutional text since the fall of the Brazilian military dictatorship, devotes significant attention to the idea of democracy. The constitution entrusts the Public Ministry, a permanent institu- tion that is crucial to the jurisdictional function of the state, with the defense of the legal order, the democratic regime, and so-called metaindividual interests and rights—rights belonging to society as a whole. The protection of the en- vironment, claimed as a common possession for use by the people and recog- nized as essential to a healthy quality of life for current and future generations (Article 225), is a metaindividual right. The defense of rights fits into the larger scope of implementing the essen- tial principles of the Federative Republic of Brazil. As Marcelo Goulart reflects: The strategic goal of the Public Ministry is to defend the project of participative, economic and social democracy outlined in the 1988 Constitution through achievement of crucial objectives for the Re- public, synthesized in Article 3, from Section I to IV (construction of a free, fair and solidary society in which cultural and socio-economic development should be directed towards the eradication of poverty and marginalization, thus reducing social and regional inequalities and promoting the welfare of all). In order for the Public Ministry to fulfill this task, the Brazilian Constitu- tion gives it legitimacy to adopt measures of civil and criminal liability against the violators of environmental rules.1 The authors would like to thank Mr. Matt Moorhead, the editors of this volume, Dr. Nigel Quinney, Gustavo Abreu, and Alessandra de Souza Santos, who collaborated on the techni- cal revision and translation of this text. 1 M. Goulart, Princípios institucionais do Ministério Público: A necessária revisão conceitual da unidade institucional e da independência funcional MPMG Jurídico, 14 Belo Horizonte 13 (Oct./ Dec. 2008). 315 The World Bank Legal Review316 The expansion of the power of the Public Ministry and other public agen- cies to protect the environment is vital in a country undergoing intense eco- nomic development. The use of law as a means of environmental protection is a way to compensate for the negative impacts of the increasing demand for natural resources. In this sense, the constitution of 1988 established “state activism” in regard to ecological matters in Brazil.2 According to the 1988 constitution, the Public Ministry’s functions are to promote, on an exclusive basis, public criminal action and to institute civil in- vestigations and public civil actions for the protection of the environment and other metaindividual interests. As the legitimate defender of these interests, the Public Ministry plays the role of “society’s attorney” even against the state itself, because, in the Brazilian legal system, the Public Ministry is assured of operational independence. Thus, the Public Ministry is a public institution, attached to the state, but, as constitutional defender of society’s interests, it is independent from the state. This feature guards against any forms of viola- tion of metaindividual rights, including violations committed by agents of the state. Goulart notes that the operational independence of the Public Ministry “is a social guarantee because it was created to give people security of having a political agent which, while acting for the defense of social interests, can work independently, immune to the pressures of power.”3 This chapter looks at the ways in which the Public Ministry, and espe- cially the Public Ministry of the State of Minas Gerais, has used innovative legal mechanisms to address and resolve environmental and social conflicts. The chapter focuses in particular on a successful initiative to reorganize the ministry’s environmental work so that it corresponds to natural, rather than administrative, boundaries. The Problem-Solving Public Ministry: The Extrajudicial Activities of the Public Ministry The Public Ministry has the power to resolve environmental conflicts without demanding the intervention of the judiciary. This power is exercised via two instruments: • A recommendation, through which the Public Ministry sends the state guidelines to improve the provision of a service of public interest • A “conduct adjustment,” a type of out-of-court settlement through which a person or company that has put at risk or has caused damage to the public interest (for example, environmental quality) assumes obligations 2 This chapter is based on a draft of a chapter from a forthcoming book tentatively titled Law, State, and Development: New State Activism in Brazil in Comparative Perspective and edited by David Trubek, Helena Alviar, Diogo Coutinho, and Alvaro Santos. 3 Goulart, supra note 1, at 12. The Role of the Public Ministry in the Defense of the Environment 317 to cease the illegal activity, to conform conduct to legislation, and to repair damage done The out-of-court settlement, known as a term of conduct adjustment (TCA), has helped remove red tape from the processes of environmental con- flict resolution, which are frequently complex, thereby avoiding court dis- putes that could drag on for years. The Public Ministry thus plays a problem- solving role: it offers quick responses consistent with the socioenvironmental demands of the society. The Drainage Basin as a Territorial Unit for Analysis, Planning, and Action An analysis of socioenvironmental processes and planning strategies cannot be isolated from the context of the natural systems in which they occur. In this context, the drainage basin is suitable for an investigation that aims to integrate physical, biotic, social, cultural, and economic aspects, providing an understanding of the ways in which different environmental aspects—such as vegetation cover, geology, and agricultural production systems—interact.4 Drainage basins are multilevel systems that encompass political, economic, and cultural practices and as such are an important environmental and social area for analysis and planning. As Francisco Barbosa, João Antônio de Paula, and Roberto Monte-Mor comment: [A] “basin” has considerable merit as a physical and economic unit for analysis. Actions or policies external to the “basins” (pricing policies, for example) can have important effects within a system defined in them, and an economic analysis, even incorporating the issue of welfare, can capture only a part of the relevant interactions within the system. Appropriate management requires, therefore, that the basins be considered as “multilevel” systems that include water, soil, and sociopolitical components, internal and external. Thus, a typical “basin” would consist in the overlap of natural and social systems. The natural system would be defined on aquatic and terrestrial (fauna, flora, water resources, and minerals) bases. The social system would determine how these bases are used. Govern- ment policies as an extension of social and institutional organization influence local patterns of using natural resources.5 4 R. G. M. Botelho, Planejamento ambiental em microbacia hidrográfica, in Erosão e conservação dos solos: Conceitos, temas e aplicações 269–300 (A. J. T. Guerra, A. S. Silva, & R. G. M. Botelho ed., Bertrand Brasil 1999); and F. V. F. Castro, L. J. Alvarenga, & A. P. A. Magalhães Jr., A Política Nacional de Recursos Hídricos e a gestão de conflitos em uma nova territorialidade, 1(1) Geografias, Belo Horizonte 37–50 (2005). 5 F. A. R. Barbosa, J. A. Paula, & R. L. M. Monte-Mor, A bacia hidrográfica como unidade de análise e realidade de integração disciplina, in Biodiversidade, população e economia: Uma região de Mata Atlântica 258 ( J. A. Paula coord., UFMG/Cedeplar/ECMXC/PADCT/CIAMB 1997). The World Bank Legal Review318 Brazilian law recognizes the drainage basin as the territorial unit for envi- ronmental planning, management, and analysis. Law 8,171/1991, which con- cerns agricultural policy in Brazil, states, “The drainage basins constitute the basic units for planning [for] the use, conservation, and recovery of natural resources” (Article 20). Law 9,433/1997, known as the Water Law because it established the National Policy of Water Resources, also focuses on the drain- age basin as the territorial unit (Article 1, Section V). Although the Water Law presents several innovations, such as the adop- tion of socioenvironmental parameters, its application, like the application of environmental laws in general, has been marked by conflicts. Some of them derive from the coexistence of territorial units corresponding to the adminis- trative units of Brazil’s federation (union, member states, municipalities, and Federal District) with the natural divisions of drainage basins and ecosystems that they encompass. In other words, the geographic areas covered by the ad- ministrative units do not correspond to the geographic area of drainage ba- sins. As Jorge Thierry Calasans et al. point out: [B]ecause the implementation of water resources management by basin does not coincide with the political-administrative division of the country, it creates a potential conflict between the entities that are part of SINGREH [National System of Hydric Resources Man- agement]. The so-called water resources management agencies must now give up their administrative autonomy over the management of water resources in the state’s territory to share their autonomy with the new deliberative body represented by the Basin Committees.6 Similar conflicts have been identified regarding the environmental protec- tion provided by the Public Ministry. The Public Ministry is organized, like the judiciary, by counties, which creates several obstacles to prosecutors’ work to protect environmental and water resources. These obstacles are identified by Antônio Herman Benjamin and include • “County likeness,” the concept that environmental and water resources can be safeguarded using the geographic and legal organization into counties, despite the fact that this method of organization is incompatible with the natural division of the natural systems. • “Spontaneism,” which prevents proactive and prospective action by the Public Ministry, whose work is reactive and retrospective. Thus, ministe- rial intervention is “always hostage to the degradation which has already occurred or is just about to occur, subjugating the institution to the fait accompli dictatorship.” • “Lack of specific techniques for the correct interpretation of environ- mental issues,” which substantially restricts activities by the prosecution offices in defense of the environment. Lacking technical and scientific 6 J. T. Calasans et al., A Política Nacional de Recursos Hídricos: Uma avaliação crítica, in Congresso Internacional de Direito Ambiental 7°, Anais 585–602 (Imprensa Oficial 2003). The Role of the Public Ministry in the Defense of the Environment 319 resources, the prosecution offices have problems identifying and measur- ing complex environmental problems. • “Generalism,” which hinders the expertise of prosecutors with regard to knowledge of environmental law, “hampering the implementation of en- vironmental legislation and providing an inadequate service to our cus- tomers, the community, and the future generations.” • “Isolationism,” which precludes the “efficient use of the institution’s ener- gies, leading to a shortsighted implementation, if not devoid of any real practical results, because it lacks the overall vision,” that is, the view on the drainage basin to be protected as a whole.7 Benjamin is convinced that “environmental problems recognize neither the historic strength of the criterion of administration of the jurisdictional rules that guide the division of the state into counties, nor the political frag- mentation of the territory.”8 Proposals for the territorial reorganization of the Public Ministry in the interest of environmental protection are gaining ac- ceptance. The idea that ministerial action should have drainage basins as a basis—that action should be taken not on the basis of political units (coun- ties) but on the basis of hydrogeographical regions (drainage basins)—would foster, in geographical and socioenvironmental terms, a more comprehensive view of ecological problems and their socioeconomic and cultural constraints and implications. It would also encourage the development of ecologically ef- fective solutions that are socially appropriate. The Public Ministry of Minas Gerais State (MPMG) pioneered the imple- mentation of a drainage basin approach. In 2001, with the support of the federal government, MPMG created the Prosecution Office of the Rio Sao Francisco Drainage Basin and started planning and enforcing actions to pro- tect natural and water resources associated with Rio Sao Francisco, consid- ering the drainage basin as a whole. Before that, MPMG actions occurred in a fragmented way throughout the several counties (administrative geo- graphical divisions, as opposed to natural ones) in the state. The Prosecution Office of Rio Sao Francisco is subdivided into five regions devoted to the preservation and restoration of natural and water resources from the drain- age basin. In 2009, this working model was extended to all other basins and sub-basins within the territory of Minas Gerais state, effectively coordinat- ing regional prosecution offices in their work to defend the environment. This reorganization of MPMG received social and institutional recognition in Brazil when it was awarded the Innovare Prize in 2010 in the Public Min- istry Award category. 7 A. H. Benjamin, Um novo modelo para o Ministério Público na proteção do meio ambiente, 10 Re- vista de Direito Ambiental 7–13 (Apr./Jun. 1998). The quoted material is from page 11. 8 Id., 10. The World Bank Legal Review320 Conflict Resolution and the Promotion of Environmental Quality Using the drainage basins of Minas Gerais as its basis and applying a problem- solving approach, the reorganized MPMG has been effective in resolving environmental conflicts in the state, as evidenced by a number of programs. Between November 2008 and November 2011, prosecutors considered a total of 13,906 cases but submitted only 4,795 of them—that is, just 34 percent —to the courts. Conflict resolution through the formalization of out-of-court settlements, employing TCA, was used in 66 percent of cases (9,111 proce- dures). MPMG was involved in the defense of protected areas (53 percent of TCAs), the repair of environmental damage (22 percent), pollution control (8 percent), the protection of wildlife (3 percent), and the control of irregular mining (2 percent). MPMG thus expanded its conflict-resolution role by implementing a set of extrajudicial techniques geared specifically toward the negotiation of environ- mental conflicts involving the protection of metaindividual and unavailable rights. In parallel, it instituted environmental damage valuation as a refer- ence for the evaluation of “ecological compensation”—in other words, for an evaluation of procedures aimed at the improvement of environmental well- being according to the provisions of the Brazilian Constitution (Article 225, paragraph 1, Sections I, II, and VII) and the National Environmental Policy (Federal Law 6,938/1981, Article 2, Sections I, II, IV, VIII, and IX, and Article 4, Section VI). It is difficult to translate into monetary terms the damage that environ- mental degradation can cause. Such degradation has multiple, cumulative, and synergistic impacts. Many valuation methods exist, but none can cope with the diversity and variety of the damage caused. The inability to predict the value of compensation for environmental degradation hinders the adop- tion of agreements. For this reason, ecological compensation has become the most appropri- ate way to solve many socioenvironmental conflicts, especially in regard to the need to restore the damaged area. Ecological compensation also helps the company responsible for the damage to determine how to conduct its future activities so that it abides by the law, in the sense that by being held respon- sible for ecological damage, the company will be reeducated in environmen- tally friendly ideals. Serra da Moeda An example of the success of this approach can be seen in the Serra da Moeda (Mountain of Money) case. As a result of the decisions made in this case, a mining company whose activities could have caused serious damage to the environment stopped extracting ore in areas relevant to biological diversity conservation. These areas were turned into “conservation units”—that is, areas given special protection by environmental legislation. The Role of the Public Ministry in the Defense of the Environment 321 In the Serra da Moeda, a mining company sought to carry out activities in an area believed to have high environmental value. The ensuing debate revolved around the question of how one can reconcile environmental preser- vation with the generation of jobs and income, considering the socioeconomic development of the region, in accordance with Federal Law 6,938/1981, Ar- ticle 4, Section I. MPMG defined the area that would be crucial to environmental preserva- tion. No mining activities—indeed, no human activities that cause environ- mental damage—would henceforth be allowed in this area. Following careful studies, the company identified other areas in which it wanted to mine and presented an initial schedule for the extraction of ore. Subsequently, the com- pany submitted to a regular environmental licensing process, carried out by Minas Gerais State, obtaining an authorization for mining in the areas defined as exploitable in the agreement signed by the Public Ministry. Oasis The Oasis project is another example of MPMG’s role as a protector of the environment. This project was implemented through an agreement signed in 2011 by the Public Ministry and a mining company from the town of Bru- madinho. In the course of a civil investigation, MPMG found evidence of en- vironmental damage and quantified the environmental compensation. The compensation consisted of payments to 75 small producers around the min- ing venture whose farms included Permanent Preservation Areas (PPAs)— for example, river banks and hilltops—and Legal Reserve Areas—portions of property deemed necessary for the sustainable use of natural resources, biodi- versity conservation, shelter, the protection of native flora and fauna, and the preservation of the quality, amount, and circulation of water resources in the environment. In partnership with the Foundation O Boticario, MPMG developed a methodology to specify the monthly amount to be paid to each farmer, as well as an efficient system of inspection that demonstrated whether benefi- ciaries were afforded adequate funds to maintain the Legal Reserve and the PPAs. The partnership between MPMG and the foundation is innovative: this is one of the first projects in this state based on payment for environmental services (PES). It also contributes to social and environmental justice because it remunerates farmers who contribute to the implementation of environmen- tal legislation. Belo Horizonte A third example of MPMG’s expanded role involves the protection of the quality of life in the urban environment. In 2011, entrepreneurs from the real estate market in the southern section of the Minas Gerais capital, Belo Ho- rizonte, signed a breakthrough agreement with MPMG. The civil building sector has a number of negative consequences with regard to the quality of urban environment, especially for urban mobility, and it increases demand The World Bank Legal Review322 for public services. Again, environmental compensation was the solution: 20 entrepreneurs committed themselves to a road construction project in the neighborhood, considered a priority by the associations of local residents. The agreement with MPMG was made with input from Minas Gerais State and the consent of the city of Belo Horizonte, representing the local commu- nity. Thus, there was a widespread effort to improve the quality of life in the urban environment. Conclusion The Public Ministry, notably in Minas Gerais State, has distinguished itself as an institutional defender of Brazil’s environment. It enhances the effectiveness of the state’s response to various types of socioenvironmental conflicts in two major ways: it prioritizes conflict-resolution work—that is, work that does not require the intervention of the courts; and it recognizes the need to reconfigure the territorial organization of institutions so that they are consistent with the organizational pattern of the natural systems. The Public Ministry has thus been able to expand access to justice and to implement the laws that protect natural and water resources in Brazil. 323 OHADA Nears the Twenty-Year Mark An Assessment Renaud BeauchaRd On October 17, 1993, in Port Louis, Mauritius, 14 African heads of state signed a treaty creating the Organization for the Harmonization of Business Law in Africa, or Organisation pour l’Harmonisation en Afrique du Droit des Affaires (OHADA). The treaty came into force on September 18, 1995, and its signato- ries now number 17 member states.1 Designed to modernize and harmonize business laws with the ultimate goal of increasing domestic and foreign trade and investment, OHADA constitutes a unique experiment involving the legal integration of states participating in different economic, trade, and monetary unions.2 Almost two decades after the Port Louis treaty was signed, this chap- ter evaluates the initiative.3 That task is not made easier by the fact that little empirical evidence sug- gests that OHADA has had a beneficial effect on the economies of the member states, all of which are lower-tier countries crippled by structural problems and most of which have experienced numerous calamities since the creation of OHADA, including humanitarian crises, military coups, and the collapse of democratic governments.4 The main issues analyzed here are whether any cor- relation can be identified between the good and bad fortunes of the OHADA member states and OHADA itself and whether OHADA can provide a work- able basis for attracting investment in its member states. OHADA was first conceived of during a meeting of finance ministers of the members of the Communauté Financière Africaine5 held in Ouagadou- 1 In order of ratification, the OHADA member states are Guinea-Bissau ( Jan. 15, 1994), Senegal ( Jun. 14, 1994), Central African Republic ( Jan. 13, 1995), Mali (Feb. 7, 1995), the Comoros (Feb. 20, 1995), Burkina Faso (Mar. 6, 1995), Benin (Mar. 8, 1995), Niger ( Jun. 5, 1995), Côte d’Ivoire (Sep. 29, 1995), Cameroon (Oct. 20, 1995), Togo (Oct. 27, 1995), Chad (Apr. 13, 1996), the Republic of Congo (May 28, 1997), Gabon (Feb. 2, 1998), Equatorial Guinea (Apr. 16, 1999), Guinea (May 5, 2000), and Democratic Republic of Congo ( July13, 2012). See http://www .ohada.org/etats-parties.html. 2 The Economic Community of West African States (ECOWAS), the West African Economic and Monetary Union (UEMOA), and the Monetary and Economic Community of Central Africa (CEMAC). 3 Parts of this chapter draw significantly on R. Beauchard & J. Kodo, Can OHADA Increase Legal Certainty in Africa, Justice and Development Working Paper No. 17/2011 (World Bank 2011), available at http://siteresources.worldbank.org/EXTLAWJUSTINST/Resources/17 -2011CanOHADAIncrease.pdf?resourceurlname=17-2011CanOHADAIncrease.pdf. 4 Including the events in Guinea-Bissau and Mali unfolding at the time of writing. 5 The Communauté Financière Africaine (CFA) franc is the name of two currencies used in Africa that are guaranteed by the French treasury: the West African CFA franc (XOF) and http://www.ohada.org/etats-parties.html http://siteresources.worldbank.org/EXTLAWJUSTINST/Resources/17-2011CanOHADAIncrease.pdf?resourceurlname=17-2011CanOHADAIncrease.pdf http://www.ohada.org/etats-parties.html http://siteresources.worldbank.org/EXTLAWJUSTINST/Resources/17-2011CanOHADAIncrease.pdf?resourceurlname=17-2011CanOHADAIncrease.pdf The World Bank Legal Review324 gou, Burkina Faso, in April 1991. This group of experts, led by Justice Keba Mbaye from Senegal,6 was appointed to conduct a feasibility study on a form of legal collaboration designed to promote economic integration and attract investments.7 Integration could be attempted via several methods. It could take the shape of a common frame of reference or a model law, which the states could then use as a point of reference, without any obligation.8 Another, more con- straining, approach would be to establish objectives to be pursued and let the states determine how to implement them.9 A still deeper form of integration could be attained through unification, that is, by replacing preexisting national laws with uniform laws.10 Unification would substitute new legislation for current domestic laws in relevant areas of business. In the end, OHADA framers chose the path of unification,11 although the treaty expressed this goal by using the all-encompassing—though perhaps more ambiguous—word “harmonization.” As part of the process, a new set of unified laws was created that preempted all conflicting domestic provisions. The treaty was opened to all African states, whether or not they were mem- bers of the African Union. A fully fledged international organization, OHADA has an institutional framework that consists of the Council of Ministers (Conseil des Ministres), the Permanent Secretariat (Secrétariat Permanent), the Common Court of Justice and Arbitration (Cour Commune de Justice et d’Arbitrage, or CCJA), and the Regional Training Center for Legal Officers (Ecole Régionale Supéri- eure de la Magistrature, or ERSUMA). The treaty revisions signed in Québec on October 17, 2008, completed the institutional framework with a fifth the Central African CFA franc (XAF). Although theoretically separate, the currencies are ef- fectively interchangeable. 6 Keba Mbaye died in 2007 after having occupied the offices of chief justice of the Senegalese Supreme Court, chief justice of the Senegalese Constitutional Council, and vice president of the International Court of Justice. 7 Martin Kirsch, Historique de l’OHADA, Revue Penant 129 (1998); Barry Walsh, In Search of Success: Case Studies in Justice Sector Development in Sub-Saharan Africa 44 (World Bank 2010). 8 For example, US model codes or the Association Capitant and Société de Législation Com- parée’s Draft Common Frame of Reference on European Contract Law. 9 For example, European Commission (EC) directives. 10 Comp. EU regulations are the most direct form of EU law—as soon as they are passed, they have binding legal force throughout every member state, on a par with national laws. National governments do not have to take action themselves to implement EU regulations; see http://ec.europa.eu/eu_law/introduction/what_regulation_en.htm. For more details, see J. A. Yakubu, Community Laws in International Business Transactions, in Unified Business Law for Africa: Common Law Perspectives on OHADA 4 (Claire Moore-Dickerson ed., GMB Publishing 2009). Although harmonization is mentioned in the treaty, OHADA in fact uni- fies business law, but the (French) word “harmonisation” was used instead of “unification” consciously and for political reasons. 11 See Keba Mbaye, L’histoire et les objectifs de l’OHADA, 205 Les Petites Affiches 6 (2004). http://ec.europa.eu/eu_law/introduction/what_regulation_en.htm OHADA Nears the Twenty-Year Mark 325 component, the Conference of Heads of State and Government. The revised treaty came into force on March 21, 2010. The main accomplishment of OHADA has been the production of a series of standardized pieces of legislation on business law, known as uniform acts, which are directly applicable in the member states and preempt any relevant domestic legislation. Thus far, nine uniform acts are in force.12 With most uniform acts in force for more than a decade, it is legitimate to ask whether OHADA has produced the desired effects identified in the Port Louis treaty’s preamble, which proclaims the aim of “making progress toward African uni- ty and creating a climate of trust in the economic systems of the contracting States with a view to creating a new center of development in Africa.” Who Are OHADA’s Constituents and What Can OHADA Bring Them? A preliminary matter in assessing OHADA is to identify its constituents. Al- though this should be an easy task, in fact, the political elites in OHADA coun- tries tend to think of OHADA constituents as judges, lawyers, notaries, and bailiffs, all of whom like to participate in donor-funded seminars on more or less theoretical subjects. But while these are indeed essential actors, OHADA constituents must be more broadly defined. Geographically, the best place to locate OHADA constituents is in the many marketplaces that characterize Africa. For the purpose of this chapter, the Dantokpa market in Cotonou (Benin), one of the largest marketplaces in West Africa, is the focus. A fascinating place, it is a complex, multilayered, pyramidal structure. The base consists of minor transactions in local goods, usually perishable and cheap. The next level is fabrics, jewelry, and arts and crafts, more expensive and often transported from far away. At the very top of the pyramid is the active money market. What is most important in places like Dantokpa is not what appears at first sight. It is the credit, rather than the commodities. The Dantokpa market is where accounts are settled, where debts meet and cancel each other out. The complex structure operates almost entirely outside the realm of formal law and ignores OHADA. Therefore, when considering OHADA, one should think about the small merchants at the Dantokpa market as OHADA’s con- stituents. What precise innovations can OHADA bring its constituents to empower them and promote their welfare? OHADA offers the business community of the OHADA member states some essential “institutions” (in the neo-institu- tionalist sense of the “humanly devised constraints that structure political, 12 The uniform acts cover general commercial law, companies, secured transactions, bank- ruptcy, arbitration, simplified debt collection and enforcement measures, accounting, carriage of goods by road, and cooperative companies. The World Bank Legal Review326 economic and social interactions”)13 that can transform uncertainty, which is characterized by imprecise knowledge, into risk, which relates to events that can be assessed with some degree of certainty and can therefore be hedged against.14 It can provide universal mechanisms that ensure that its constitu- ents are not liable for 100 percent of their losses. It can give its constituents institutions such as pledges without dispossession, which allow them to use their stock as collateral for a loan. It can help the moneylending observed in places like the Dantokpa market ascend to the next level, that of commercial moneylending. The drafters of OHADA had small merchants in mind when they defined OHADA’s ambitious policy goals. But somewhere along the way, OHADA’s lofty objectives came into conflict with the entrenched economic logic of autocracy and rentseeking15 at play in the member states, which typically sup- port contract or property rights enforcement only for regime insiders. Legal Certainty: The Fundamental Standard Achievement of the OHADA policy goals should be the ultimate measure of OHADA’s success. The Port Louis treaty aims at “making progress toward African unity and creating a climate of trust in the economic systems of the contracting States with a view to creating a new center of development in Af- rica.” The important word here is “trust,” which French anthropologist Marcel Mauss describes as “the very foundation of all collective action.” The economies of the OHADA member states are mostly informal and broken into a mosaic of local markets; trust is precisely the engine that could help achieve the aim of OHADA to transform member economies from ones based on a material life focused on survival to an economic life focused on ex- change. This goal can be achieved only through larger-scale, more integrated markets, which require two pillars of trust: property protection and contract enforcement. More fundamentally, trust points to and underlines another central concept articulated in the Port Louis treaty: legal certainty. Because legal certainty connotes more than a simple evaluation of a law’s formulation but encompasses the issues of enforcement and observance, this chapter evalu- ates OHADA against the critically important objective of legal certainty. The standard of legal certainty must be clearly defined, however, which is not necessarily an easy task. Taking into account that a definition must be 13 See Douglass North, Institutions, 5 J. of Econ. Persp. 97 (1991). 14 See H. Root, Capital and Collusion: The Political Logic of Global Economic Development 4–6 (Prince- ton 2006). 15 Rentseeking is a culture in which the principal route to wealth is not creating wealth but taking possession of or benefiting from wealth created by others. Financial Time Lexicon, available at http://lexicon.ft.com/Term?term=rent_seeking. http://lexicon.ft.com/Term?term=rent_seeking OHADA Nears the Twenty-Year Mark 327 comprehensive but not too far-reaching, this chapter first uses an operational a contrario definition of what legal certainty is not. And there is no better ex- ample of what legal certainty is not than the situation found in the member states in pre-OHADA days. At that time, outdated business laws existed on the books, but without implementing regulation and often in contradiction to existing or prior nonabrogated norms. Having no equivalent of specialized commercial courts and with negligible business litigation, business law was largely an abstraction in those countries. What is more, judges had no codes and little if no access to legal reports or periodicals, and they often ignored the issue of which laws applied to which economic activity.16 Without effec- tive risk management, legal innovations, such as limited liability companies or secured transactions, which are so essential to the successful advance of industrial revolutions, were doomed to remain at the margin of economic de- velopment. This situation was among the ills OHADA hoped to redress. Is it possible to propose a formulation of the legal certainty standard relative to OHADA’s ambitions? Keep in mind that OHADA unifies busi- ness laws, the main objective of which is the protection of modern property rights17 and contract enforcement—and here is a useful limit to the definition of legal certainty that also limits the scope of the investigation. The protection of property rights and contract enforcement requires, in the words of Oliver Wendell Holmes, that “people . . . know under what circumstances and how far they will run the risk of coming against what is so much stronger than themselves[,]” which meant “the incidence of the public force through the instrumentality of the courts.”18 That knowledge presupposes “that all law be sufficiently precise to allow the person—if need be, with appropriate advice— to foresee, to a degree that is reasonable in the circumstances, what a given action may entail.” This means that with respect to harmonized business laws: • laws and decisions must be public and publicly available; • laws and decisions must be definite and clear in their applicability; • decisions of courts must be enforced and, to the greatest extent possible, reasoned, so as to provide relevant information on the compliance of con- duct with law; and • persons or officials associated with the application and enforcement of those laws must be easily identifiable and properly trained and equipped to accomplish their duty. 16 See, e.g., the dismal description made by Xavier Forneris, Harmonizing Commercial Law in Africa, 46 Juris Périodique 77, 81 (2001), available at http://www.ohada.com/doctrine /titre/199/Harmonising-commercial-law-in-Africa-the-OHADA.html. 17 Francis Fukuyama’s definition of modern property rights is used here, understood as “rights held by individuals, who are free to buy and sell their property without restrictions imposed by kin groups, religious authorities, or the state.” Francis Fukuyama, The Origins of Political Order 248 (Farrar, Strauss & Giroux 2011). 18 Oliver Wendell Holmes, The Path of the Law, 10 Harv. L. Rev. 457 (1897). http://www.ohada.com/doctrine/titre/199/Harmonising-commercial-law-in-Africa-the-OHADA.html http://www.ohada.com/doctrine/titre/199/Harmonising-commercial-law-in-Africa-the-OHADA.html The World Bank Legal Review328 Assessment of OHADA in Regard to Legal Certainty The goal here is to assess OHADA’s innovations and claim of empowering member states’ populations against the standard of legal certainty, as artic- ulated above. To promote legal certainty, OHADA is based on two pillars: the norms it produces and the institutions designed to produce and apply those norms. OHADA has largely been successful in terms of the production of norms. There are undeniable achievements, mostly concerned with the innovations contained in the formulation of OHADA law and centered on the supranational level, which are detailed here. However, OHADA has en- countered serious challenges regarding the application and the reception of the uniform acts. OHADA has an Achilles’ heel: the way it is implemented at the state level. Only if the focus is on effective implementation can OHADA deliver results; this, however, does not seem to be the case. Achievements In a remarkably short period of time, OHADA has created a new suprana- tional organization—no small feat. The principal achievement of OHADA is that it has largely fulfilled its aim in the production of uniform law. Thus far, OHADA has delivered nine uniform acts that form an innovative, comprehen- sive, definite, and coherent framework focused primarily on the microlevel, the level of the productive unit. For example: • The General Commercial Law Act provides the fundamental rules of business activity: merchant status, commercial leases, commercial sale of goods, agency, businesses and movables registry (Registre du Commerce et du Crédit Mobilier, or RCCM), and microbusiness. • The Companies Act provides for various limited liability structures that protect business operators. • The Secured Transactions Act provides for various securities protecting creditors against the risk of defaults of their debtors and sets the condi- tions for the development of commercial lending. • The Accountancy Act provides for uniform accounting standards based on the true and fair view standard. • The Simplified Debt Collection Procedures and Enforcement Measures provides operators with modern legal remedies, such as seizures and garnishments, that are available to unpaid judgment creditors to compel judgment debtors to pay up, if need be with the assistance of the police. The OHADA drafters opted for a uniform law rather than a harmonized one. OHADA is not a model code, which the member states are free to adapt. It is a uniform set of legislation that must be applied with consistency in the member states. On one hand, this uniformity makes implementation less dependent on the governments of the member states, although that is largely theoretical. On the other hand, the policy choice of a uniform law makes it ap- pear more distant from its ultimate constituents and more difficult to reform to respond to local circumstances. OHADA Nears the Twenty-Year Mark 329 But uniformity means nothing without coherence. In this respect, the co- herence of OHADA law rests primarily on Article 10 of the treaty, which pro- vides that the uniform acts preempt all domestic statutes for the subject matter they cover, whether enacted before or after the acts’ entry into force. And there cannot be coherence without uniformity of interpretation. Thus, to guarantee uniformity of interpretation, the OHADA framers created the court of justice, the CCJA. Some examples of innovations that, if properly applied, could have an important impact on OHADA’s constituents, include the following: • The entreprenant status: the General Commercial Law Act, revised in 2010, introduced a status of entreprenant, inspired by the auto-entrepreneur status in France, which is credited with leading more than 300,000 persons to register an activity in less than a year after its introduction in 2009. • The Registre du Commerce et du Crédit Mobilier (RCCM): the General Commercial Law Act created a three-tiered registry of businesses and movables, the RCCM. This registry, by recording businesses and movable securities, is an important and essential innovation designed to ensure protection for creditors. As such, it is a key institution to favor the devel- opment of moneylending. • Pledges without dispossession on tangible assets: the Secured Transac- tions Act, revised in 2010, instituted pledges without dispossession on tangible assets. Provided it becomes a practical reality, this is a welcome innovation designed to use stock or any other means of production as col- lateral without depriving the grantor of the use of the pledged asset. A Few Design Flaws Even though the formal law created by OHADA was well conceived, it is not flawless. For example, why did the drafters consider a bankruptcy act to be a priority in countries with no significant commercial moneylending? As one author put it, “bankruptcy is the unwanted handmaiden of commercial debt.”19 Without significant commercial lending, there is no practical use for a bankruptcy act. This act should have been implemented farther down the road. The choice of arbitration as the sole alternative dispute resolution method was introduced in OHADA to the detriment of mediation, which would cor- respond better with the traditional method of conflict resolution known as pa- labre.20 Arbitration is a hard sell in OHADA countries. Perceived as expensive, the payment of fees up front is often dissuasive, except for very sophisticated businesses. Mediation and conciliation, which, compared with adjudication, 19 See Wade Channell, Lessons Not Learned about Legal Reforms, in Promoting the Rule of Law Abroad, in Search of Knowledge 141 (Thomas Carothers ed., Carnegie 2006). 20 See J.-G. Bidima, La palabre, une juridiction de la parole (Michalon 1997). The World Bank Legal Review330 are costless alternatives and centered on consensus building, would be easier to sell. Finally, only two uniform acts (the General Commercial Law Act and the Commonly Owned Businesses Act), and one only very partially, acknowledge the existence of an informal sector, which accounts for 60 to 85 percent of the GDP of the member states.21 But these challenges are easy to address in comparison to implementation challenges. Implementation Challenges Diligent application of the existing uniform acts should be the priority of OHADA policy makers. Except for employment law—and not everybody agrees on that—the OHADA institutions should stop legislating activity and dedicate attention to the enforcement of the existing uniform acts. The legislation of risks generates conflicts with norms produced by other regional organizations. Thus, the more legislation there is, the more oppor- tunities there are for conflicts with other regulatory ensembles, because all OHADA member states are also members of monetary unions, such as the Union Economique et Monétaire Ouest Africaine (UEMOA), and trade and customs unions, such as the Economic Community of West African States (ECOWAS). These groups produce regulations, especially in the banking sec- tor. Only once markets become more concentrated should OHADA legislate further. Regarding proper implementation, OHADA faces various challenges, beginning with the institutional challenges of OHADA itself. OHADA must transform itself into an integrated judicial space in which final judgments on subject matters covered by OHADA are given full faith and credit. Finally, and this is certainly the most difficult challenge, OHADA can succeed only if member states demonstrate the requisite level of political will and dedication to implement OHADA laws. Institutional Challenges At the regional level, OHADA institutions are well established. However, they still face budgetary constraints. For example, the total budget of OHADA in 2012 was roughly US$8.3 million, which seems low, especially considering that OHADA must organize an annual conference of heads of states.22 More important, there seem to be structural problems (not least the use of bud- 21 See Prosper Backiny-Yetna, Secteur informel, Fiscalité et équité, l’exemple du Cameroun, 104 Sta- téco (2009); Mireille Razafindrakoto, François Roubaud, & Constance Torelli, La mesure de l’emploi et du secteur informel: Leçons des enquêtes 1-2-3 en Afrique, 104 Statéco (2009). 22 See Minutes of the Council of Ministers (Dec. 15 & 16, 2011), available at http://www.ohada .org/actualite-cm/en/cmfj/actualite/3610-compte-rendu-de-la-reunion-du-conseil-des -ministres-de-lohada-des-15-et-16-decembre-2011-a-bissau.html. http://www.ohada.org/actualite-cm/en/cmfj/actualite/3610-compte-rendu-de-la-reunion-du-conseil-des-ministres-de-lohada-des-15-et-16-decembre-2011-a-bissau.html http://www.ohada.org/actualite-cm/en/cmfj/actualite/3610-compte-rendu-de-la-reunion-du-conseil-des-ministres-de-lohada-des-15-et-16-decembre-2011-a-bissau.html http://www.ohada.org/actualite-cm/en/cmfj/actualite/3610-compte-rendu-de-la-reunion-du-conseil-des-ministres-de-lohada-des-15-et-16-decembre-2011-a-bissau.html OHADA Nears the Twenty-Year Mark 331 get) that indicate that simply injecting money won’t do the trick. Among all OHADA institutions, the one that seems to be suffering the most is the CCJA, which has backlogs despite a rather modest caseload.23 One structural problem can be traced to the treaty itself, which provides that all matters of interpretation of an OHADA provision as a matter of law can be deferred only to the CCJA, which cannot refuse to hear the case if it deems that the matter does not raise any matter of uniform interpretation at the regional level. Although this tenet may appear sound in theory, it has led to difficulties in administrative manageability and has made backlogs unavoid- able. Although this provision does remove the final interpretation of OHADA law from the national judiciaries, which are often accused of cooptation by political forces and extractive interests and of solving conflicts of interpreta- tion of OHADA provisions even before states review the matters, it also risks causing jurisdictional conflict with domestic supreme courts and hampers the CCJA’s manageability, a critical problem given the scarcity of resources in the member states. To make matters worse, the Rules of Procedure (Réglement de Procédure) contain no provision for filtering appeals such as those existing before the US Supreme Court, which grants plenary review to an average of only 1 percent of the cases on its docket, or for fast-track proceedings such as those insti- tuted before the French Cour de Cassation in 2001.24 Such proceedings would give the CCJA the ability to refuse to hear a case by a nonreasoned decision if it deemed that the appeal, which is limited to a matter of legal interpreta- tion, does not raise interpretative issues requiring a CCJA decision. Instead, Article 26 of the Rules of Procedure requires that as soon as an appeal is lodged, the CCJA chief justice must appoint a judge to follow up the case management and report to the court. This is the same procedure used by the French Cour de Cassation before the institution of the fast-track option in 2001, a reform motivated by the buildup of large backlogs. No Integrated Judicial Space There is no real judicial space in OHADA, that is to say, a space where final and enforceable decisions of the national judiciary on OHADA matters receive full faith and credit in OHADA member states applying the same law based on a simple recognition and enforcement procedure. Although the treaty pro- vides that CCJA judgments are directly enforceable in the territory of mem- ber states under the same conditions as domestic judgments (Article 20 of the Rules of Procedure), it does not contain any jurisdictional provision for transnational matters, nor does it regulate how final domestic judgments that apply uniform law can be applied in other member states. 23 It is difficult to understand how a court with nine judges can have backlogs with a docket of a few hundred cases, as compared, for example, with the US Supreme Court, which has the same number of judges and an annual docket of 10,000 cases but little backlog. 24 Known as procedure de non admission du pourvoi. The World Bank Legal Review332 Because of this shortcoming, issues of jurisdiction, recognition, and en- forcement within the OHADA judicial space tend to follow national rules, which suffer from the same problems as the laws OHADA replaced: they are frequently outdated, unavailable, unenforced, and/or nonexistent. Challenges at the State Level Perhaps the most prominent example of OHADA’s enforcement weakness is the Business and Movable Securities Registry (RCCM). The RCCM operates at three levels: local, national, and regional. A creation of the general commercial law that entered into force in 1998, the RCCM is largely a virtual registry. Most discussions have been centered on computerization, viewed as the remedy of all ills. Computerization suffers from its own problems, not least the lack of coordination among actors involved in the process, but the issue has much deeper roots than that. First, the initial filings are made at the local level, then at the national level, and finally at the regional level and little progress can be attained if the focus goes the other way around, that is, from the regional to the local. Second, and this is the more important problem, a registry of collat- eral cannot be feasible without a proper vital records registry, which none of the member states has managed to create. Another implementation issue is the articulation of the uniform acts and domestic laws the OHADA acts are intended to replace. In domestic circum- stances, new text replacing another indicates that the provisions of older in- struments are repealed. That is called express abrogation. Express abrogation is difficult with a supranational law, such as OHADA laws; article 10 of the treaty provides that the uniform acts are “directly ap- plicable and mandatory . . . against any contrary provision in domestic law.” Thus, OHADA is an example of tacit abrogation. To make OHADA work, the member states should have inventoried all texts repealed by OHADA and enacted express abrogation statutes. Yet, not a single country has done that. At best, a proper inventory was made, but no statute has been enacted to repeal preempted instruments. At worst, nothing has been done. In most cases, hefty fees have been paid to consultants to make insufficient inventories. As a result, OHADA provisions coexist with tacitly repealed domestic rules, not a tenable situation regarding legal certainty. These are just some of the implementation challenges that call for the in- tervention of the governments of the member states. But these are nothing in comparison to the challenges caused by the necessity to ensure that OHADA becomes a concrete reality for its constituents. In this respect, a reconsidera- tion of the Dantokpa market is in order. The constituents of OHADA are not the judiciary and the various legal professions (attorneys, bailiffs, notaries, and the like) of OHADA member states, but rather the business community, comprising mostly informal actors. To reach their true constituents and be effective, OHADA’s laws must be implemented and applied by a myriad of intermediary players, including OHADA Nears the Twenty-Year Mark 333 accountants, moneylenders, court registries, chambers of commerce, business registration units, microfinance institutions, banks, insurance companies, ar- bitration and mediation chambers, and all sorts of government officials in- volved in activities connected with the constitution of capital and the protec- tion of property for business. But OHADA remains largely an abstraction for those actors. To guarantee the integration of OHADA into domestic legal systems, a first and logical step would have been to carry out an inventory of all agents affect- ed by OHADA and to ensure that these actors are familiar with OHADA and comply with it. To provide one example: the websites of most business regis- tration centers say nothing about the status of entreprenant or microbusiness. In the OHADA member states, the status of entreprenant exists only virtually. Similarly, formalization cannot take hold without the cooperation of tra- ditional leaders in rural communities. Nothing was done to familiarize tradi- tional authorities with the advantages of mechanisms such as those promoted by OHADA to transform uncertainty into risk management. Conclusion OHADA has come a long way since the 1993 Treaty of Port Louis. Few ob- servers would have expected that a group of states whose track record on coordination was decidedly wanting would be able to achieve the goal of stan- dardizing business laws. The framers of OHADA and international donors as- sumed that the appropriate social and political institutions required for the ex- periment to succeed already existed. In retrospect, it was overly optimistic to assume that a set of uniform business laws would be self-enforcing and gener- ate trust toward and among countries in which rent seeking is so entrenched and whose judiciaries are crippled by backlogs, corruption, lack of planning, and limited accountability. Twenty years after the Port Louis treaty, it is time to reintroduce those exogenous parameters into the debate on OHADA. 335 Legal Innovation for Development The OHADA Experience Marc Frilet In the years following the independence of the French African colonies, inter- national investors and the African business community faced many difficul- ties in ascertaining the applicable principles of company law in the region.1 At that time, company law was based on the French Company Act of 1867, which ceased to be in force in France in 1966. Interpretation of the law by local courts was often hazardous, and few reliable precedents existed. This uncertainty was the source of numerous disputes that triggered often unpredictable deci- sions by local courts, which in turn caused yet more uncertainty and discour- aged international investment in these countries. This volatile situation presented an opportunity for French law firms to develop a practice in Africa providing “authoritative interpretations” of com- pany law. These interpretations were often based on documentation that was not available in Africa. The firms’ comparatively easy access to French case law gave them lucrative opportunities in Africa.2 It took years to figure out how to overcome this problem. In 1963, Profes- sor René David, a leading scholar in comparative law, organized a confer- ence with the ministries of justice of the former French African colonies to assess the need to harmonize the legal system in the interest of economic de- velopment. This meeting set the stage for the emergence of the Economic and Custom Union of West Africa in 1964 and the Economic Community of West African States in 1972. Subsequent enlargement of the scope of these organi- zations included their extension into the insurance sector during the African conference on insurance markets in 1972. The African and Mauritius Office for Law Research and Studies (Bureau Africain et Mauritien de Recherches et d’Etudes Législatives, BAMREL) was created in 1975. The purpose of BAMREL was to help signatory states develop their legislation in a harmonized manner. Although BAMREL was not imple- mented due to a lack of funding,3 its conception represents the true beginning of the harmonization of business law in the region. 1 The OHADA region comprises 17 states: Benin, Burkina Faso, Cameroon, the Central African Republic, Chad, the Comoros, the Democratic Republic of Congo, the Republic of Congo, Equa- torial Guinea, Gabon, Guinea, Guinea-Bissau, Ivory Coast, Mali, Niger, Senegal, and Togo. 2 See also Georges Meissonnier & Jean-Claude Gautron, Analyse de la législation africaine en matière de droit des sociétés, 3 RJPIC 331 (1976). 3 See Alhousseini Mouloul, Comprendre l’organisation pour l’harmonisation en Afrique du Droit des Affaires, 2nd ed., Working Paper 17 (2008). The World Bank Legal Review336 The desire of the business community (both in Africa and farther afield) to develop a secure legal system for economic transactions was increasingly expressed, particularly by private operators and the French Council for Inves- tors in Africa (CIAN). In April 1991, during the conference of Ouagadougou (Burkina Faso), which included all the ministries of finance of the franc zone, the decision to progress toward the harmonization of African francophone countries was made. The ministries of finance gave a mandate to a high-level panel of seven members, made up of eminent jurists and specialists in busi- ness law, to propose an action plan. The panel was chaired by Keba Mbaye, a Senegalese judge and a former vice-chair of the International Court of Justice. In October 1992, in a meeting of the heads of state in Libreville (Gabon), the report of the panel was presented and endorsed by President Abdou Diouf.4 The next step was to appoint a directoire, made up of three members, to coordi- nate and prepare a treaty creating the Organisation pour l’Harmonisation en Afrique du Droit des Affaires (OHADA, also known as the Organization for the Harmonization of Business Law in Africa). The directoire was chaired by Mbaye and included Martin Kirsch, honorary counselor of the French Cour de Cassation, and Michel Gentot, chair of the dispute department of the French Conseil d’Etat. After preparation of the draft treaty and several meetings with experts, judges, and specialists, 14 states5 signed the treaty in Port Louis (Mau- ritius) on October 17, 1993;6 the treaty was revised in Quebec (Canada) on October 17, 2008.7 Many of the exchanges were organized under the leadership of Keba Mbaye, especially during the conference in Abidjan in 1993, where techniques for preparing to harmonize business law were presented and tested (inter alia, through the organization of national committees in each country). A key objective of OHADA, as reported by Seydou Bâ, former chair of the Senegalese Court de Cassation and former president of the OHADA regional supreme court (the Common Court of Justice and Arbitration, or CCJA), is to progressively unify the legal framework in the area of business law and to organize a set of legal procedures promoting harmonized and sustainable development in all the Member States. Harmoniza- 4 The final communiqué is as follows: The heads of states “approved the project of harmoni- zation of business law elaborated by the Ministries of Finance of the Franc Zone, decided its immediate implementation, and requested to the Ministries of Finance and Justice of all interested States to treat this matter as a priority.” Henri Tchantchou, La supranationalité judiciare dans le cadre de I’OHADA: Etude à la luminère du système des communautés européennes 22 (L’Harmattan 2009). 5 The 14 signatory states are Benin, Burkina Faso, Cameroon, the Central African Republic, Chad, the Comoros, Equatorial Guinea, Gabon, Ivory Coast, Mali, Niger, the Republic of Congo, Senegal, and Togo. 6 See http://www.ohada.com/traite.html. 7 See http://www.ohada.com/traite-revise.html. http://www.ohada.com/traite.html http://www.ohada.com/traite-revise.html Legal Innovation for Development 337 tion of business law is a real trigger of growth and should facilitate the implementation of the rule of law.8 Legal integration is intended to mirror progress in economic integration at the regional level between Central African and Western African states. To this end, the OHADA member states designed a set of Uniform Acts on business law matters.9 The nine OHADA Uniform Acts cover three broad areas: • Commercial relationships and related transactions (general commercial law, security law, transport of goods by roads) • Establishment and operation of commercial entities (company law and economic interested groups, accounting law) • Settlement of disputes and regulation of commercial default (arbitration, bankruptcy law, recovery procedures) Additional acts are in the pipeline for contract law and labor law. The acts are currently under review on the basis of a reform program or- ganized by the World Bank Group’s multidonor Investment Climate Advisory Service (FIAS). The overall project objective is to improve the quality and ef- fectiveness of the legal and institutional framework created by OHADA and therefore help the 17 member countries increase their attractiveness for do- mestic and foreign private investment.10 OHADA is a major legal innovation, unique in the modern world. There is much to be learned by assessing it. This chapter looks at its impact from a private sector perspective. The Positive Features of OHADA Several OHADA Uniform Acts replaced old business regulations in partici- pating countries. This move has generally been welcomed by international and local businesses that wish to develop their operations in a secure frame- work and with good governance. The best features of OHADA include the following: 8 Seydou Bâ, speech, in Fourth International Conference on Law and Economy: La convergence du droit 48–50 (Ordre des avocats de Paris, Edition Lamy Nov. 2005). 9 The Uniform Acts relate to general commercial law, commercial companies and economic interest groups, securities, recovery procedures and measures of execution, proceedings for wiping out debts, arbitration, undertakings’ accounting systems in the signatory states to OHADA, carriage of goods by road, and cooperative credit banks. 10 The reform’s program has three components: 1, institutional strengthening of the OHADA Secretariat and project implementation support: to strengthen the institutional capacity of the Permanent Secretariat; 2, institutional strengthening of the Joint Court of Justice and Arbitration (CCJA) and the regional superior magistrate school (ERSUMA); 3, improving corporate financial reporting: to improve and strengthen corporate financial reporting, accounting standards, professional standards and practices, regional professional qualifica- tions, and so on. The World Bank Legal Review338 • The process of drafting, developing, and promulgating the Uniform Acts is efficient by all modern standards. • Problems often found in other countries or regions for drafting and adopt- ing new pieces of legislation are minimized in the OHADA countries. • The problem of striking an appropriate balance between general prin- ciples and concepts and specific language is satisfactorily resolved. The Uniform Acts are worded in plain language that is easy to understand, with a minimum of cross-references and definitions. Credit must be given in this respect to the innovative method for the initial drafting of the Uni- form Act, which was to invite international law firms to participate. • The Uniform Acts are limited to key areas of business laws and as such are not particularly politically sensitive. For instance, the Uniform Acts do not cover areas that are often considered sovereign privileges, such as mining, taxation, and criminal penalties. The Uniform Acts are conducive to good governance and economic devel- opment. In this respect, some were designed to educate the users (members of the business community, especially the local business community). This is par- ticularly relevant for the OHADA company law system. As noted by Professor Guyon, the OHADA company law system—as is the case in many civil law countries—is more institutional than contractual in character.11 He reminded his audience that a role of law is to protect third parties, and the Uniform Act Relating to Commercial Companies and Economic Interest Groups does just that. In his view, OHADA company law could become more contractual in the future as the economy and the capacity of the players develop. Article 2 of the Uniform Act Relating to Commercial Companies and Eco- nomic Interest Groups states: “The provisions of this Uniform Act are manda- tory, except in cases where the Act explicitly authorizes a sole partner or the partners of a company to substitute contractual provisions between them for those of this Uniform Act or to supplement the provisions of this Uniform Act with their own provisions.”12 11 IBA Conference on OHADA, Yaoundé (Cameroon), December 1999. 12 Some international experts and scholars who view this act more from a common law per- spective may consider it too rigid and not conducive to the facilitation of business activities. If this is true for some sophisticated players, it is not the case for most of the African busi- nesses that need strong guidance and strict boundaries to develop their businesses with legal certainty before reaching the stage of sophisticated techniques. This is an important point to take into account in a “doing business exercise” sponsored by the World Bank. For instance, the obligation to have articles of association drafted or recorded with a public notary has raised debate. For most of the new players in the OHADA region, this obligation is perceived as an element of facilitation of business and governance, and in particular legal certainty for third parties. For some others, it may be considered an unnecessary hurdle limiting the pos- sibility of easily creating a company. Another debate has been raised concerning the benefits or pitfalls of having a minimum paid-up capital as provided for in the OHADA Uniform Acts. In the OHADA region, this provision is perceived less as a constraint to creating business than as a facilitation of sus- Legal Innovation for Development 339 Some Uniform Acts induce the informal sector of the economy to develop activities in the formal sector by providing for the following: • Registration of commerce and movable credit (RCCM) • Disclosure of corporate documentation • Accounting: The Uniform Act on accounting is generally recognized as a compromise in this respect, taking into account the real situation in the region13 • Progressive access to lines of credit through mortgages and pledges • Simplified forms of company structure, including mandatory provisions for their organization and operation The response of the business community in Africa to OHADA has gener- ally been positive.14 The international legal community also has responded positively. An American Bar Association panel made a thorough evaluation of the Uniform Acts and in 1999 proposed useful guidance in various areas.15 The Implementation Challenges of OHADA As with any new legal system, understanding of and compliance with the new regime can be a challenge, especially in Africa because of the overall low level of income, the poor state of the judiciary, the size of the informal sector, and deficiencies in governance. This section discusses some key implementation challenges of OHADA for the business community and for investors. The interpretation and enforcement of the Uniform Acts by the region’s judiciaries is and will remain a significant problem. At the highest level, the CCJA renders authoritative judgments concerning the interpretation of the Uniform Acts16 and has an impressive track record. However, many decisions concern procedure and jurisdiction, and relatively few concern the substance tainable business activities, because there is no sophisticated banking system and traditional security is difficult to organize and implement. 13 Professor Pérochon, famous for his manual assisting small businesses and owner-managers, was the author of this act. He was a practitioner of both the French system of accounting rules and international accounting standards. 14 The IFEJI/UBIFRANCE survey was conducted in 2003 with the support of the local business community, Conférence Permanente des Chambres Consulaires Africaines et Francophones (CPCCAF), and the Syndicat des Entrepreneurs Français à l’International (SEFI). The answers to the 30 survey questions are a useful reference for appraising issues faced by the business community and proposed actions. 15 A team of US lawyers and judges had reviewed each Uniform Act (four to eight experts for each Uniform Act) . Other reviews were prepared by members of the section of International Law and Practice of the American Bar Association (ABA) and the International Judicial Rela- tions Committee of the United States Judicial Conference under the leadership of William Hannay (OHADA project chair and chairman of the section of International Law and Prac- tice of the ABA), together with two rapporteurs. 16 Paul Gerard Pougoué & Sylvain Sorel Kuate Tameghe, Les grandes décisions de la cour com- mune de justice et d’arbitrage de l’OHADA (L’harmattan 2010). The World Bank Legal Review340 of the law. The CCJA also provides advice to national governments and judi- ciaries that is authoritative but limited. The greatest challenges facing the CCJA are its location, resources, and relationship with national judiciaries. Because of its location in Abidjan and its limited resources, the CCJA cannot perform its functions in an optimum man- ner. The problem of distance is a major issue for most of the OHADA states, and one that is negatively seen by practitioners in various countries and the international community. The superior courts in member states have resisted acknowledging that the CCJA possesses ultimate jurisdiction. Furthermore, many judges have only limited knowledge of OHADA. OHADA also includes a comprehensive and unique system of arbitration. Yet, the CCJA also has the authority to conduct arbitration and to rule on ad- ministrative issues. However, because this function is not well understood by the private sector and is underused, the number of authoritative awards is limited. The OHADA arbitration rules are modern and in accord with interna- tional standards, but they need to be implemented by administrative services provided by the secretary of the arbitration court. So far, the track record of implementation is limited. Promoting the arbitration system has proved to be a challenge. The system requires improvement in several aspects.17 Another challenge relates to the enforcement of the Uniform Acts in terms of criminal sanctions. Without appropriate criminal sanctions, compliance with legislative provisions is haphazard. The OHADA approach to criminal penalties is interesting in this respect. Article 5, paragraph 2, of the treaty pro- vides that “[t]he Uniform Acts may include provisions to give rise to criminal liabilities.” Article 10 provides that “Uniform Acts are directly applicable and overriding in the Contracting States notwithstanding any conflict they may give rise to in respect of previous or subsequent enactment of municipal laws.” Because the Uniform Acts are directly enforceable in each member state, criminal offenses should also directly be sanctioned in each member state. However, Article 5, paragraph 3, provides that “Contracting States commit themselves to enforce sentences of offences.” Thus, the sanction for criminal offenses is in fact determined by each state. This situation entails enforcement problems and discrimination, because the member states are not harmonizing penalties. This conundrum occurs not only with prison sentences and fines but also with surety provisions and other procedures for enforcement.18 17 Improvements could include, for instance, the introduction of more prescriptive procedural rules and guidelines governing the appointment and performance of the arbitrators, clarifi- cation of foreseeable costs depending on various procedural aspects and organization of the proceedings, and decentralization of the arbitration’s administration. 18 Aude-Marie Cartron & Boris Martor, Eclairage sur la révision du Traité de l’OHADA, 36 Cahier du Droit de l’Entreprise no. 1 ( Jan.–Feb. 2010). Legal Innovation for Development 341 This situation is compounded by the fact that it is not always easy to iden- tify in the Uniform Acts the definition and scope of a criminal offense. Some of the acts, such as the Uniform Act on Recovery Procedures and Measures of Execution, are particularly complex in this regard.19 Legal or Regulatory Areas Not Regulated Many key areas of interest to investors are not covered by the OHADA Uni- form Acts, including • Taxation and issues of tax certainty and conditions of implementation • Parafiscality20 • Customs and related tariffs • Exchange control and currency fluctuation issues • Private contract law content and interpretation21 • Public contract law content and interpretation • Permitting risks (risks deriving from governmental or bureaucracy atti- tude for clearances, nonobjection, approval, and other permits) • Land availability and land use risks, including the expropriation process and related issues • Environmental impact studies and related permits • Administrative or judicial review of adverse bureaucratic decisions • Public-private partnership issues • Employment law risks 19 Michel Mahouve, Le système pénal OHADA ou l’uniformisation à mi chemin, Recueil Penant 87–94 ( Jan.–Mar. 2004). 20 Parafiscality is recognized as a major risk for the business community and investors. It is broadly defined as the fees, royalties, local and sundry taxes, and levies not directly listed and not defined in tax code or legislation, mostly payable at the local level or with line min- istry organizations, for supporting particular activities or services of such administration and/or public bodies. In most states, parafiscality charges are numerous and in constant development. 21 Several drafts of Uniform Acts are in circulation, but little progress has been made on an avant-projet of Uniform Acts since February 2008. One reason is that this avant-projet is too close to the UNIDROIT principles. Various meetings have been held on the subject since September 2012, including exchanges between the French Institute of International legal Ex- perts (IFEJI) and the African professors Issah-Saygeh, Pougoué, and Sawadogo on Septem- ber 2008 (as part of the activities of the international working group set forth by IFEJI with the support of the World Bank and various stakeholders in March 2005: “Legal reform in developing countries—evaluation of the OHADA model”). A comparative analysis has been made on the drafting process and through benchmarking with the European Union effort to assess the benefits of a common European contract law. In Europe, this uniform contract law is progressively taking shape after the publication of a common frame of reference for its harmonization and a tentative draft of an optional legal instrument for international sales published in 2011. The World Bank Legal Review342 At this point, large international investment projects can realize only limited benefits of OHADA because OHADA does not regulate most major risks.22 Yet these kinds of projects are essential for development in areas such as infrastructure, public utilities, and mining. Business Community Expectations The business community expects that OHADA will contribute to the legal formalization of day-to-day activities, including relationships with states, ministries, public entities, subsovereign entities, and the like. This business community is represented at different levels, particularly with the chambers of commerce.23 French investors, who are very active in francophone Africa, have devel- oped a French business community in Africa, represented by the Conseil Fran- çais des Investisseurs en Afrique (CIAN) and the Mouvement des Entreprises de France (MEDEF). Members of these organizations are in close contact with African and international lawyers.24 In the eyes of the international business community, better and more effi- cient implementation of the existing Uniform Acts is needed. Three tasks need particular attention: • Reinforce the program run by the ERSUMA school in Benin (see below) to train the judiciary. • Design a user-friendly system that encompasses the issues of a particu- lar region and the capacity of the players and then promote arbitration through this system. This means, inter alia, doing the following: • Guarantee the appointment of an arbitration tribunal that is indepen- dent, professional, and efficient. • Guarantee simple and well-understood proceedings in line with local traditions for dispute resolutions. • Guarantee a fair and enforceable award within a reasonable time. 22 In areas that necessitate major up-front investments and with a very long recovery capacity (often over several decades), it is interesting to analyze the risk matrix developed by the industry leaders and that led to a due diligence ending at limiting the risks at a reasonable level to finance the project. For instance, in large mining projects, the risk matrix identifies 10 to 20 key chapters in which several key issues are generally identified. Some chapters can be well appraised in appropriate regulations, procedures, and reasonable perspectives of good implementation. Examples are expropriation, land use, compensation, resettlement, environmental permits and environmental and social management plans, and sovereign in- terference. 23 Several chambers have developed an integrated system of exchanges and created entities such as the Conférence Permanente des Chambres Consulaires Africaines et Francophones (CPCCAF). 24 In particular, the French Institute of International Legal Experts (IFEJI), created by the Paris Bar, and the French Ministry of Foreign Affairs select French practitioners (on average, 120 practitioners) with day-to-day expertise in international business law matters. Legal Innovation for Development 343 • Guarantee an arbitration administration center that is efficient, re- sponsive, fair, and cheap. • Allow the possibility of evaluating in advance costs and duration of proceedings. • Promote the development of uniform “implementing regulations,” guide- lines, and procedures for the Uniform Acts. In considering additional Uniform Acts, two actions may do most to help foster international investments in Africa: • Design an institutional framework that will facilitate long-term public- private relationships in the core public service sector with appropriate guarantees for the stakeholders and a limited impact on state budgets and development aid. • Design principles of public contract law and procedures that facilitate transactions involving the public sector. These should include improve- ment in the procurement of public contracts of all kinds and the provision of reasonable guarantees of fair implementation of the various types of contracts between the private and the public sectors, together with effi- cient procedures in areas such as mining contracts, urban development, forestry, lease of public land, and agriculture projects. Capacity Building and Empowerment Issues The international community has been actively building capacity in the OHADA region. For example, the ERSUMA school in Porto-Novo (Benin), which conducts training for the judiciary,25 provides support to OHADA in- stitutions such as the OHADA national committees. Yet, it is clear that much remains to be done in terms of capacity building and empowerment in regard to OHADA. The OHADA model has been assessed with a view to further improving the lawmaking process and the legal certainty for the business community. Sev- eral international working groups with that focus were established in the mid- 2000s, particularly in the wake of two conferences organized by the Paris Bar inviting African experts and practitioners, as well as World Bank specialists, in Washington (2004) and in Paris (2005).26 These exchanges led to the creation of a joint working group on legal reforms in developing countries, which has as its objectives the evaluation of OHADA and the dissemination of lessons learnt. The World Bank Group is playing an important role in funding programs to evaluate the content and implementation of the Uniform Acts through the World Bank Group’s multidonor Investment Climate Advisory Service 25 See http://web.ohada.org/ersuma.html. 26 The World Bank was represented by Robert Danino, senior vice president and general coun- sel of the World Bank, and Michael Klein, chief economist of the IFC (World Bank). http://web.ohada.org/ersuma.html The World Bank Legal Review344 (FIAS). This effort has resulted in a useful revision and improvement of some Uniform Acts (relating to securities and general commercial law), and other acts are in the pipeline (relating to competition law, banking law, intellectual property law, civil societies law, and evidence).27 The international donor com- munity is also supporting the OHADA institutions. More work is needed to build capacity in OHADA institutions and to imple- ment provisions on the ground. Specific areas that require attention include • The efficient implementation of the Trade and Personal Property Credit Register, an instrument for securing transactions and developing the economy • The organization and selection of the judiciary • The organization of efficient and user-friendly arbitration centers • The process of designing and implementing in various states regulations that further develop and adapt the OHADA Uniform Acts at various lev- els, including the clear abrogation of national regulations that conflict with the Uniform Acts Josette Nguebou, professor of law at the University of Yaoundé (Camer- oon), explored the sensitive relationships between the Uniform Acts and the national laws of the member states. She found that “although national law not conflicting with the Acts remained applicable, nothing prevents the Mem- ber States from maintaining and expending regulations which could narrow down its scope or even prevent its effective implementation.”28 Capacity building and empowerment should also be oriented toward • Fostering exchanges between scholars and practitioners on the implemen- tation of the Uniform Acts and authoritative case law. • Training the legal profession in the international business law system. • Training senior civil servants to engage with the international business community in order to permit them to be on an equal footing with expe- rienced international players when negotiating, implementing, and moni- toring their relationships. This would apply, for example, to projects in the oil and gas sector, the mining sector, the infrastructure sector, the utility sector, the agricultural sector, and the forestry sector. • Enabling more extensive exchanges between the local administrations and the administrations of other countries and regions. • Implementing more proactive programs in e-learning. Well-prepared pro- grams of e-learning, including appropriate documentation transmitted in 27 See the harmonization agenda adopted by the Council of Ministers of the OHADA region during the Bangui meeting of March 2001. 28 See OHADA Treaty, Les actes uniformes commentés et annotés, Juriscope 249 (1999). On this matter, see also Marc Frilet, Implementing the Rule of Law in Sub-Sarahan Africa: Appraisal of the OHADA after a Decade, 8(3) Bus. L. Intl., 254–67 (Nov. 2007). Legal Innovation for Development 345 advance by electronic means and used as background material for work- shops or specialized classes, can be effective at building capacity. The programs should be monitored by teachers or facilitators who have been trained to teach in an e-learning manner, including, when appropriate, direct online contact with authoritative scholars in other countries.29 • Fostering new relationships between the public and private sectors to ease the transfer of investment. This was identified as a top priority by multi- laterals and by the G20 Business Summit in Cannes (also referred to as the B20 of Cannes) in November 2011. Infrastructure development is seen as essential to achieving the Millennium Development Goals, and to that end the business community has been urged to develop a framework for better projects.30 Proposals have been made to design a new act on PPP; in June 2011, the council of ministers of OHADA decided to explore that option. Perfecting a system of equitable public contract law based on concepts and case law should be a priority, especially because some OHADA countries have started to experience the benefits of equitable public contract law for both the private sector and the public sector in landmark and long-term public infrastructure and utility projects. Conclusions OHADA has many positive features, and lessons learned from its implemen- tation can be instructional for organizations considering business activities not only in that region but also in other regions of the world. Improved understanding of the Uniform Acts will help strengthen the in- vestment climate and make it easier to do business in the region. Particular attention should be given to a clearer definition of criminal offenses (including the nature and scope of the criminal penalties). One solution might be to pro- mulgate a Uniform Act on this matter.31 29 E-learning conducted by faculties of law deserves to be taken into account; see, for instance, development of e-learning under the auspices of the International Bar Association (IBA). 30 See G20/B20, Final Report of the Business Summit in Cannes, 8 (Nov. 2011). In relation to pub- lic-private partnerships, the G20 report (p. A-71) says, “without appropriate institutional and legal framework, most of the public-private partnership (PPP) projects proposed for developing countries have a high likelihood of failure.” An international working group made of international lawyers with expertise in concession and other PPPs worldwide and representatives of the construction industry has been working on the matter with various agencies for a few years. This group, after reviewing many projects with governments and local authorities, identified 30 issues that need to be addressed in an inclusive manner for the success of long-term concessions and other PPP projects. The publication of a handbook on the conditions of success of concessions and other PPPs, together with an evaluation matrix for concession on other PPP projects, individually or at an institutional, regulatory, or con- tractual level, is expected in 2012. See CICA website, http://www.cicanet.com/. 31 See Achille Ngwanza, OHADA, Entre adolescence et âge adulte, une crise existentielle, Rapport général de l’université d’été de cercle horizon, club OHADA d’Orléans ( Jul. 1–3 2008). http://www.cicanet.com/ The World Bank Legal Review346 The greater problem is that regulatory sectors essential for the economic development of Africa, which are not well controlled by national laws or re- gional organizations, are not yet regulated by Uniform Acts. Looking ahead, it is important to consider new Uniform Acts in key areas where a good regula- tory framework already exists. It is also essential to launch an innovative pro- cess of capacity building and empowerment in the various directions outlined above, such as developing exchanges between scholars and practitioners, and training members of the legal profession and senior civil servants. Greater participation of legal practitioners experienced in providing advice in Africa may be the key to this process.32 Laurent Esso, minister of justice of Cameroon and president of OHADA, reported on the collateral benefit of OHADA in terms of legal innovation. In his view, OHADA is a conduit for convergence between civil law and common law in business law matters. He believes that Cameroon could be a laboratory for facilitating the implementation and interpretation of the OHADA Uniform Acts due to its unique civil law/common law regimes.33 Professor Barthélemy Mercadal, a specialist in international business law, followed this path by pro- moting convergence in the interpretation of legal concepts worldwide (inter alia, between the civil law and the common law worlds) based on the same or similar legal provisions and using the OHADA Uniform Acts as a background. Mercadal’s extraordinary effort, which led to a publication of Code IDEF annoté de l’OHADA,34 will contribute to encouraging business players at both the na- tional and the international levels to use the Uniform Acts on a regular basis.35 OHADA is an advanced and inclusive example of legal innovation for development. As such, the OHADA Uniform Acts are an excellent ground on which to test the benefits of an emerging field focusing on the optimization of legal frameworks and products. Although the contribution of OHADA to this field is already significant, much more can be done to apply lessons for further legal innovation.36 32 Business community and legal practitioners active in this area include UNIDA, CIAN, MEDEF, IFEJI, and IBA, which have conducted several conferences. 33 Uniform Commercial Law Infrastructure and Project Finance in Africa, 215 Intl. Bus. L. (May 2000). 34 http://www.institut-idef.org/-Code-OHADA-annote-.html. 35 See also Marc Frilet, Le raisonnement juridique du monde anglo-saxon: Quelques considérations élémentaires et quelques recettes pour éviter les malentendus contractuels, in La revue des entreprises (MEDEF Jan. 2000). 36 For information on this emerging field, known as l’art de la légistique, see Carine Gilberg, L’art de la légistique, Gazette de Palais 8–10 ( Jan. 6–7, 2010); Alexander Flückiger & Christine Guy-Ecabert, Guider les parlements et les gouvernements pour mieux légiférer—le rôle des guides de légistique (Schulthess 2008); Guide pour l’élaboration des textes législatifs et réglementaire, avail- able at http://www.legifrance.gouv.fr/html/Guide_legistique_2/accueil_guide_leg.htm; Catherine Bergeal, Savoir rédiger un texte normatif (Berger-Levrault 2004); Marc Frilet, Le code civil, une source d’inspiration inégalée pour améliorer la sécurité juridique en matière internationale, 87 Revue de l’Avocat Conseil d’Entreprise (Dec. 2003). http://www.legifrance.gouv.fr/html/Guide_legistique_2/accueil_guide_leg.htm http://www.institut-idef.org/-Code-OHADA-annote-.html Page numbers in italics refer to figures and tables. access to justice, 69, 179–180, 185–190, 195, 198 Accra Agenda for Action, 132 administrative forfeiture procedure, 269–270 administrative law, 182–184 Administrative Law on Urban Land and Real Estate Property (2007; China), 195 administrative reform, 7–8 Africa, 13–14, 142–143, 335–346 African and Mauritius Office for Law Research and Studies (BAMREL), 335 African Peer Review Mechanism, 142 Agreement on Trade-Related Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights (TRIPS), 13, 89–91, 311–312 AIDS. see HIV/AIDS Ain O Salish Kendra (ASK), 75, 79–81, 84 Gender and Social Justice Program, 80 Albright, Madeline, 35 Americans with Disabilities Act, 61 Amet, Arnold, 240, 242 antidiscrimination law, 195–197 antimoney laundering programs, international, 265, 279 appeals system (China). See Petition system (China) Arab Spring, 260–264 arbitration, 70, 73–74, 184, 189–190 Arbitration Act (1996; United Kingdom), 225 asset forfeiture. See Asset recovery and International asset sharing programs asset recovery, 9–10. See also Asset sharing Arab Spring and implications for, 260–264 conditions for, 259–260 due diligence in, 254–255 mutual legal assistance procedures and, 262–264 prevention of corruption in, 254 three stages of, 259 asset sharing, 9–10. See also Asset recovery and International asset sharing programs Australian Agency for International Development (AusAID), 40 Austrian Development Cooperation, 136–137 Bâ, Seydou, 336 Banchte Shekha, 84, 87 Bangladesh, 10 Bangladesh Legal Aid and Services Trust, 81 Bangladesh National Women Lawyers Association, 77 Bangladesh Rural Advancement Committee, 79, 81, 83 Beijing Declaration and Platform for Action, 223 Belo Horizonte agreement, 321–322 Ben Ali, Zine el Abidine, 260–262 Bermuda (IASP agreement), 267–268 BHP Pty Ltd, 238, 240 Bill & Melinda Gates Foundation, 99 Bio Ventures for Global Health (firm), 96 Blue Law International, 52, 55 BMZ (Germany), 137 BNDES (Brazilian Development Bank), 284, 286–287, 289, 291–292, 294, 297, 299, 301, 304, 308–309 Bolsa Escola program, 288 Bolsa Familia program, 293, 309–310 brain drain, 92 Brasil Maior program, 291–292 Brasil Sem Miséria program, 293 Brazil, 8–9, 315 bureaucracy, 283, 294, 303, 313 constitution (1988), 283–288, 301–304, 314 developmentalism, 281–283, 287–289, 294–295, 298–299, 301–307, 309, 311, 313–314 economic policy, 282–287 competitiveness and, 285, 287, 291, 296–298, 300–302, 305, 308, 310, 313 inflation and, 283, 285, 288–289, 293, 299–300 liberalization and, 285, 294–296, 301 privatization and, 283–285, 286, 287, 294, 302 stabilization and, 283, 285, 289 economic sector financial sector, 296–299 private sector, 282, 285, 289–291, 295, 298–302, 307–313 public sector, 284, 294, 299, 302–304, 310, 313 foreign investment, 284–285, 288, 294, 300–303, 312 immunization program, 95–96 industrial policy, 287–305, 308–309, 312–313 infrastructure, 289–290, 296–299, 305 Minas Gerais, 316–322 Belo Horizonte, 321–322 neoliberalism, 281–285, 288–289, 294, 296, 306–307, 311 new developmentalism, 281–283, 288, 294, Index 349 Index350 301, 304–307, 309, 313–314 new state activism, 282–284, 288–314, 306–309 poverty alleviation, 282–283, 287–289, 292– 295, 298, 300, 305, 310, 312 public administration, 310–311 public-private partnerships, 283–285, 288– 292, 297, 301, 303, 305, 308–310 social policy, 284, 287–289, 292–295, 305, 307–310, 313 state-owned enterprises, 282, 284–285, 286, 287, 294, 298, 302 trade policy, 291, 311–312 welfare system, 283–284, 287–288, 293, 300, 309 Brazilian Agency for Industrial Development, 290, 292, 297, 306 Brazilian Development Bank. See BNDES Burton Blatt Institute, 57 business law, 323–333, 335–346 Cadastro Único (Brazil), 309–310 Canada, 143 Canada (IASP agreement), 267–268 Cardoso, Fernando Henrique, 283–290 Career Development Fellowship on Clinical Research & Development, 99 child care laws, 224 China, 7–8, 296, 305 as a developing country, 203 constitution (1954), 202–203 constitution (1975), 202–203 constitution (1982), 202–208 collective ownership in, 204–206 compensation for requisitioned land in, 210 decision-making power in, 206 distribution principles in, 204 “duty to work” in, 206 economic freedom in, 206–207 economic planning in, 205–206 economic reforms and amendments in, 207–211 economic system of, 203–207, 209 foreign investment in, 204 gender equality in, 196 human rights in, 191, 211 private ownership in, 205, 211 property rights in, 205, 210–211 public ownership in, 204–206 socialist rule of law and, 190–192 Cultural Revolution, 170–172 economic growth, 203 economic reform, 212 opening up policy, 179–180, 202 petition system, 183–184 private economy legitimized, 207–212 rule of law, 208 social change, 161, 169, 174, 176–177 social reform, 162, 171, 175–176 social security, 206–207, 211 “three supremes” policy, 192–193 Chinese Academy of Governance, 182 Chinese Communist Party (CCP), 180–181, 187, 191, 193, 199 civil law codes, 223 civil society, 10–11 civil society organizations, 217 Code of Muslim Personal Laws, 226 Collor de Mello, Fernando Affonso, 283, 285 Common Court of Justice and Arbitration, 324, 329, 331 Communist Party (China), 171 community development, 11 Community Legal Services program (Bangladesh), 68, 88 Community Mine Continuation Agreements (CMCAs), 235, 239–243, 246–48 community ownership, 247–248 family back accounts, 245–246 implementation of, 243–250 negotiations for, 239–243 scholarships, 246–247 women’s representation in decision- making, 247 community-based organizations, 79–81, 85 community-based services, 39, 43–44 community-driven development (CDD), 84, 236, 247–248 company-community disputes, 236–239 comparative law, 161–164, 166, 174, 176 conflict resolution, 5, 21–22, 68, 70–74, 77–78, 81–83, 85–88, 316–317, 320–322 conflict types, 71–73, 81, 83 constitutionalism, 7, 197–198, 211–212 democracy and, 212 economic, 202, 212 modernization and, 212 constitutions, 8, 315–316, 318, 320–321. See also China: constitution and state activism, 316 as a means of environmental protection, 316, 318 defined, 201–202 discrimination clauses, 215–216, 218 economic functions of, 201 contract law, 181–182 Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities (CPRD), 12 antidiscrimination litigation, 60–61 Conference of State Parties, 48 conflict resolution, 60 Index 351 content, 47–49 economic development, 58–59 framework for legal empowerment and innovation, 49–51 implementation, 50 reasonable accommodation, 59 structure, 47–49 Cotonou Agreement, 139–140n103 Council for Investors in Africa, 336 Council of Economic and Social Development (Brazil), 290, 297 Council of Europe Development Bank, 144 criminal justice systems, 18–19 Criminal Procedure Law (1996, China), 191–194 Cultural Revolution (China), 180–181, 186, 192, 194, 203 customary justice systems. See Traditional justice systems Dantokpa Market, 325, 332 David, René, 335 de Soto, Hernando, 35, 42 death penalty, 192 Declaration on the Right to Development. See under United Nations Democratic Republic of the Congo, 256–260 Deng Xiaoping, 179–180, 186, 199, 202, 208, 210 Department for International Development (United Kingdom), 67–68, 73, 75 Develoment as Freedom (Sen), 3 development policy, 3, 281–314 coherence, 129–145, 147–150 human rights and, 150–153 legal accountability and, 153 frameworks for, 138–144 disability (definition), 50 disability rights, 49–53 accessibility in virtual spaces, 55–58 awareness of, 49, 51–53 budget analysis, 61–63 enforcing, 59–63 facilitating, 55–58 monitoring, 59–63 policy models for, 52–55 strengthening, 53–55 disabled people’s organizations (DPOs), 48, 52, 54, 60, 63–64 dispute resolution. See Conflict resolution drainage basins. See Hydrogeographical regions Drugs for Neglected Diseases Initiative (DnDi), 13, 95 due diligence, in asset recovery, 254–255 Duvalier, Jean-Claude, 258–260 E-Court, 22 ecological compensation, 320–322 Economic Institute for Industrial Development (Brazil), 296 economic integration, 324–333 economic liberalism, 9 economic liberalization, 3 economic rights, 184–186 Egypt, 260–262 Eisai, 99 Embraer (firm; Brazil), 286, 304, 312 empowerment. See Legal empowerment entitlements as legally enforceable right, 235 family bank accounts, 245–246 scholarships, 246–247 environmental laws, 315–322 environmental protection, 9, 315–322 legal obstacles to, 318–319 urban, 321–322 equal rights law, enforcement of, 227–229, 231–232 Esso, Laurent, 346 Ethiopian Women Lawyers Association, 217 European Bank for Reconstruction and Development, 143–144 European Convention on Human Rights, 158 European Investment Bank. See under European Union European Union approaches to development cooperation, 139–144, 158 Charter of Fundamental Rights, 127, 142 Cotonou Agreement, 139–140n103 development policy coherence, 148 European Investment Bank, 141 Parliament, 141, 145, 148 Family Court of Australia, 40 family law, 6 fatwas, 74–75 Federal Act on the Restitution of Assets. See Switzerland: Return of Illicit Assets Act (RIAA) Federal Ministry for Economic Cooperation and Development (Germany). See BMZ Federation of Industries of Sao Paulo (FIESP), 295–296, 302 financial crisis of 2008, 291, 297, 312 financial markets, international, 303 Fiocruz. See Oswaldo Cruz Foundation Foundation Law (Brazil), 290 Franco, Itamar, 283, 285, 288 Gaddafi, Muammar, 261 Index352 gender discrimination (private sector), 218 gender equality, 6, 234 Gender Equality and Family Law (Kosovo), 229 gender-disaggregated data, 232 Gentot, Michel, 336 GlaxoSmithKline (GSK), 95–98 Global Forum on Law, Justice and Development. See under World Bank Global Initiative for Inclusive ICTs, 56 Global Legal Empowerment Network, 44 globalization, 295, 301 governance reform, 31, 33–34, 114–115, 120, 338 government regulation, 3, 185, 282, 286–287, 297–298, 300, 307 Growth Acceleration Program (Brazil), 297 GSK. See GlaxoSmithKline Gurry, Francis, 91 Haiti, 258–260 Harvard Law School Project on Disability, 55, 61 hepatitus B virus, 196–197 High Level Forum on Aid Effectiveness (4th), 132 HIV/AIDS, 97–98, 196 Hogares Comunitarios program (Colombia), 224 Hu Jintao, 199 human rights, 8, 11–12, 35, 58–59, 63 approaches to development, 134–136 as general principles, 133–134 disability rights, 46–49, 64 impact assessments, 157–159 in treaty frameworks, 126–127, 156 international standards, 154–156 Human Rights Protection Committee (Bangladesh), 80 hydrogeographical regions, as a territorial unit for public planning, 315, 317–322 IASPs. See International asset sharing programs (IASPs) IGD (management index; Brazil), 309–310 Indonesia, 28, 40–42, 229 industrial policy, 287–305, 308–309, 312–313 inflation policy, 283, 285, 288–289, 293, 299–300 information and communication technologies (ICTs), 56–58 inheritance rights, 219–222 Innovation Law (Brazil), 290 innovative constitutionalism. See Constitutionalism, innovative institutional reform, 293–294 institutions access to, 215 gender discrimination in education and, 221 women’s agency and, 214, 221 intellectual property, 12–13 intellectual property rights brain drain, 92 enforcement, 90, 93 pharmaceutical industry, 91–94 protection, 90–93 technological development, 92 Inter-American Development Bank Operational Policy on Indigenous Peoples, 133 International Aid and Development Agency (New Zealand), 137 international asset sharing programs (IASPs) as development mechanisms, 265–279 International Bank for Reconstruction and Development (IBRD), 101n1 International Centre for Asset Recovery, 262–264 International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, 126 International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, 126, 155 International Development Association (IDA), 101n1 International Finance Corporation, 138 international law, 11–12, 303 and disability rights, 58–59, 63 fragmentation of, 128–129, 145–158 international mutual legal assistance. See Mutual legal assistance Internet, 185–186 Japan, 53–54 Jiang Zemin, 202 Job Accommodation Network (organization), 59 Jordan, 229–230 Judges Law (China), 188 judicial administration, 186–187 judicial reform, 25–28 judicial systems access to, 179–180, 185–190, 195, 198–199 centralized, 199 sentencing, 192 justice innovation challenges, 25–27 defined, 18–19 monitoring mechanisms, 25 power relations, 27–28 research and development, 23–34 justice sector, 12 funding capacity, 18 Index 353 leadership articulating goals, 19–20 building trust, 26 considering long-term business models, 25 effecting procedural change, 20–21 fostering competition, 21–22 fostering innovation, 19–25 funding development, 23–24, 26–27 managing risk, 22–23 recognizing disruptive innovations, 24 legal reform, 45, 47 orthodoxy, 49–51 justice systems and economic development, 18, 28, 67–69, 79, 84, 88 Kabila, Laurent, 257 Kim, Jim Yong, 112 Kirsch, Martin, 336 labor law, 184–186, 195–196, 310–311 land expropriation, 194–195 land laws and rights, 219, 222–225 land reform, 194–195 law and development, scholarship on, 281– 282, 304–305 Law and Regulation Filing Office (China), 197 Law and the New Developmental State project, 306 law enforcement agencies, 269–270 Law on Gender Equality (Vietnam), 230 Law on Legislation (2000; China), 197 Law on Planification (2007; China), 195 Lawyers Law (2007; China), 187, 193–194 legal accountability, 153, 159 legal aid, 76–77, 81–82, 217, 228 legal certainty (concept), 179, 193–194, 198–200 legal development, 7, 161–177 legal empowerment, 4–6, 80 of persons with disabilities, 45, 47–51, 59, 63–65 legislative reform and, 53–54, 61–62, 64 policy reform and, 54–55, 64 of the poor, 31–15 “four pillars” of, 35–36 access to justice, 35–36, 38–40 business rights, 35–36 community-based methods, 43–44 concept, 32–34 criticism of, 36–37, 42 gender equality, 40–42 health care, 39–40 labor rights, 35–36 movement, 32–34 networks, 43–44 resistance to, by elites, 37 legal exclusion. See Rule of law, exclusion from legal expenses, 69 legal fees, 189, 198 legal harmonization, 13–14 legal innovation, 4, 14, 45, 49–51 legal integration, 335–346 legal liberalism, 9 legal obligations, 126–127 as a human rights policy frame, 136–138, 150–154 legal pluralism, 225–227 legal profession, 8, 187–188, 198–199 legal reform, 179 and sociocultural norms, 232 legal systems, 161–177, 313. See also Justice systems equal access to, 227 formal, 231–232 plural, 215 Western, 161–162, 172–173 with Chinese characteristics, 161, 169, 172–173 legal transplantation, 7 as a typical form of legal development, 161–165 conditions for success, 169–172 history of, 162–163 process of, in China, 172–177 traits and effects of, in China, 172–177 aboriginal concepts, 172–174 cost-saving approach, 167 entrepreneurialism, 168 innovation, 173, 176–177 selective adoption, 165–166, 173–175, 177 socialism, 161, 169–177 tolerance, 175–177 typology, 165–169 cost-saving, 166–167 entrepreneurial, 168 externally dictated, 167–168 legitimacy-generating, 169 legislative reform, 7, 181–182 Li Maorun v. Langzhong Police Station (2001), 183 Liberia, 52–53 Libya, 261 Limberg Principles on the Implementation of Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights, 62–63 local politics, 73–75 Lula da Silva, Luiz Inácio, 281, 287–290, 292, 294–297, 299, 301–304 Madaripur Legal Aid Association, 76–77, 82, 84, 88 Index354 Malan, Pedro, 287 Mantega, Guido, 296 Maoism, 179–180, 183, 186, 194. See also Marxism, in China Marcos, Ferdinand, 253, 261 markets, 214 marriage, 220–221 Marxism, in China, 181, 191–194. See also Maoism maternity leave laws, 224 Mbaye, Keba, 324, 336 mediation, 73–74, 184, 189–190, 198 Mercadal, Barthélemy, 346 Mexico (IASP agreement), 276–277 middle class, growth of, 291–294 Millennium Development Goals, 20, 126–128, 140n107, 221 mining industry, 10–11, 234, 320–321 Ministry of Justice (China), 180–181, 186–187 MLA. See Mutual legal assistance Mobutu Sese Seko, 256–260 Money Laundering Reporting Office (Switzerland), 255 Mubarak, Hosni, 260–262 mutual legal assistance (MLA), 254–258, 261–264 Nagorik Uddyog, 76–79, 84–85 Community Organisers, 78 Namati, 39, 43–44 National Council of Industrial Development (Brazil), 290, 292, 297 National Industry Confederation (Brazil), 296 National People’s Congress (NPC; China), 181, 185, 189, 194, 197, 202 National Policy of Water Resources. See Water Law National Strategy on Gender Equality (Vietnam), 230 natural resources as a public asset, 234 neglected tropical diseases. see NTDs negotiations, 10–11 between state, companies, and communities at Ok Tedi mine, 238–242 justice innovation and, 239 neoliberalism, 281–285, 288–289, 294, 296, 306–307, 311 Nepal, 54 Netherlands, 22 New Economic Partnership for Africa’s Development (NEPAD), 142–143 new state activism, 8, 282–284, 288–314 NGOs, 10–11, 43–44 accountability, 86–87 authority, 87 shalish and, 76–86 nongovernmental organizations. See NGOs NTDs (neglected tropical diseases), 94–97 Oasis project, 321 Official Development Accountability Act (Canada), 143 OHADA, 13–14 achievements, 328–329 arbitration system, 340 Common Court of Justice and Arbitration, 324, 329, 331, 336–337, 339–340 constituents, 325–326 directoire, 336 economic development, 338–339, 346 empowerment programs, 343–345 establishment, 323–325 implementation, 330–333 institutional framework, 324–325, 343 international community and, 342–344 international investment projects, 335, 337, 342–345 judicial integration, 331–332 legal certainty, 326–333 legal innovations, 328–333, 337, 346 regulatory functions, 341–343, 346 structural flaws, 329–330 Uniform Acts, 337–346 uniform law, 324, 328–332 Ok Tedi mine, 10–11, 235–242 Organisation for Economic Co-operation and Development (OECD), 138, 148, 312 Social Institututions/Gender Index, 9–10 Organization for the Harmonization of Business Law in Africa. See OHADA organizational representation quotas, 228–229 Oswaldo Cruz Foundation (Fiocruz), 13, 95–96 Immunobiological Technology Institute, 96 out-of-court settlements, 316–317, 320 ownership rights, 194 Palocci, Antonio, 296 Panguna mine, 236, 239 Papua New Guinea, 10–11 Western Province, 235, 237, 239 Papua New Guinea Sustainable Development Program (PNGSDP), 238 paralegals, 39, 43–44 Paris Declaration on Aid Effectiveness, 131–132 patents, 89, 96 PEKKA, 40–41, 229 People’s Courts, 182, 188–189, 193 People’s Republic of China. See China Index 355 Permanent Preservation Areas (Brazil), 321 petition system. See China: petition system Petrobrás, 284, 286, 297, 304 Pfizer Drugs for Neglected Diseases initiative and, 95 Global Health Fellows Program, 98–99 health care initiatives, 98–99 joint venture with GSK, 97–98 joint venture with ViiV Healthcare, 97–98 research on NTDs, 94–95 TDR program, 99 pharmaceutical industry, 12–13, 91–100 HIV/AIDS research, 97–98 licensing, 96–97 patents, 89, 96 regulation of, 93–94 research and development, 91–92, 94–97 technology transfer and, 94–100 vaccine development, 95–96 Philippines, 253 PITCE, 290, 301 Plano Real, 283, 285, 289, 299–300 policy making innovation, 281, 289–292, 299, 305–307, 311–314 structural elements, 297–303 political corruption, 254, 260 political economy, 290, 296, 298, 304–306, 311, 313 political economy approach (in agreement implementation), 236 political leaders. See Politically exposed persons (PEPs) political leadership, 199–200 political representation quotas, 217 political statements (international), 129–132 politically exposed persons (PEPs), 253–264 politics and law committees (China), 187, 193 Port Louis treaty. See OHADA poverty alleviation, 45, 47, 51, 282–283, 287– 289, 292–295, 298, 300, 305, 310, 312 Préval, René, 258 privatization, 5 Program for Productive Development (Brazil), 290–292 Property Law (2007; China), 194 property rights, 6, 8, 35–36, 42–43, 194–195, 205, 210, 220–221, 227–229 private, 202, 207–208, 211 public health law, 196–197 Public Ministry (Brazil), 9, 315–322 extrajudicial activities, 316–317 Prosecution Office of Rio Sao Francisco, 319 public-private partnerships, 4–5, 8, 283–285, 288–292, 297, 301, 303, 305, 308–310 Reconstruction of Aceh Land Administration System, 6–7, 222–223 Regulations. See Government regulation rehabilitation through labor system (China), 193 research and development, 23–24 revised compensation agreements. See Community Mine Continuation Agreements RIAA. See Switzerland: Return of Illicit Assets Act (RIAA) Roussef, Dilma, 288–289, 291–293, 313 rule of law, 3, 5, 161, 165, 169–171, 174, 208, 212 and development, 32–34 and empowerment of the poor, 31–35 and justice innovation, 28–29 as a measure of legal development, 179–200 assistance programs, 18 exclusion from, 35–37 innovative, 180 orthodoxy, 12, 34, 45, 48–51 plan, 20 politicization, 27 Rural Land Contracting Law (2002; China), 194 rural poor, 67–70, 74–76, 79–80, 85 Samata. See Banchte Shekha Sanctions. See World Bank: sanctions system Self-Employed Women’s Association (India), 217 Serra da Moeda, 320–321 shalish, 10 arbitration, 70, 73–74 defined, 70 NGO-organized, 76–81, 85 Sharia law, 28, 74–76 Sierra Leone, 39–40, 43–44 Social Assistance Act (LOAS; Brazil), 288 social conflict, 315–322 social control, 73–75, 85 social justice, 85–86 social policy, 9 socialism, primary stage of (concept), 209 socialist legal system with Chinese characteristics, 185 socialist market economy, 202, 208, 211 sociocultural norms, 230–231 soft law, 129–132 state-owned enterprises, 282, 284–285 286, 287, 294, 298, 302 Supreme People’s Court (SPC), 182, 186, 188–190, 192, 197 Swedish International Development Cooperation Agency, 136–137 Index356 Switzerland Federal Act on International Mutual Assistance in Criminal Matters, 255–256, 258 Federal Act Pertaining to the Sharing of Confiscated Assets, 256 Federal Council, 257–261 institutional structure, 254–256 Lausanne Seminars, 262 legal structure, 254–256 Return of Illicit Assets Act (RIAA), 256–261 Synflorix, 95 TDR (Training in Tropical Diseases) program, 99 technological innovation, 90–91 technology transfer, 12–13, 90, 91–94 term of conduct adjustments (TCAs). See Out- of-court settlements Thailand, 54–55 three represents (concept), 202, 210 traditional justice systems, 10 and international development, 85–88 obstacles to, 69–70 research on, 82–85 Training in Tropical Diseases program. See TDR Transparency International, 260 TRIPS. See Agreement on Trade-Related Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights (TRIPS) Tunisia, 25–28, 260–262 UNICEF Convention on the Rights of the Child, 137–138 Unified Judicial Exam, 187–188 Unified Social Assistance System (Brazil), 293 uniform law, 324, 328–332, 337–346. See also OHADA: Uniform Acts Union Parishads, 73–74, 77, 82–83, 88 United Nations Commission on Legal Empowerment of the Poor (CLEP), 6, 34–38, 42 Convention Against Illicit Traffic in Narcotic Drugs, 266, 268 Convention Against Transnational Organized Crime, 266 Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities (see under Convention) Convention to Eliminate All Forms of Discrimination Against Women, 214, 228 Declaration on the Right to Development, 129–130 Delivering Justice program, 17 Financial Action Task Force, 267 Guiding Principles on Business and Human Rights, 150–151, 154 human rights treaties, 135–136, 157 Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights, 131, 144, 157 Office on Drugs and Crime, 266 Respect, Protect, and Remedy Framework, 142, 150n164 support for asset sharing, 266–267 TDR program, 99 Universal Declaration of Human Rights, 35, 136–137 United Nations Development Group, 136 United Nations Development Programme (UNDP), 67, 80, 82, 85, 88 US Department of Justice administrative forfeiture procedure, 269–270 Asset Forfeiture Program, 272–273 civil judicial forfeiture procedure, 270–271 IASPs, 267–278 international sharing program, 273–278 case-specific agreements (CSSAs), 274–278 determining percentage shared, 276–277 negotiation process, 277–278 reviewing process, 275 judicial forfeiture procedure, 270 statutory authority for asset forfeiture, 268–269 Vargas, Getulio, 284–285 Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, 151–152, 158 Vienna Declaration and Programme of Action, 130 Vietnam, 230 ViiV Healthcare, 97–98 Village Courts Act (2006; Bangladesh), 82 violence against women legal pluralism on, 226–227 legislation on, 216, 223–224 sociocultural norms and, 231 Wainetti, Ume, 241–242 Wang Shenjun, 192 Washington Consensus, 282–284, 305 Water Law (1997; Brazil), 318 water resources management, 318–319 Watson, Alan, 161–166 Weimar Constitution (Germany; 1918), 201 welfare state, 283–284, 287–288, 293, 300, 309 Index 357 Wen Jiabao, 199 Western cultural influences on Chinese legal thought, 179–181, 189, 198 WIPO (World Intellectual Property Organization), 13, 91, 312 WIPO Re:Search, 8–9 Women in Mining (conference), 235 Women’s Legal Empowerment program, 41–42 women’s rights, 6, 10–11, 74–75, 77–79, 84–87 economic participation, 224–225, 227, 231 employment, 216, 224–225 entitlements as legally enforceable right, 235 family bank accounts, 245–246 scholarships, 246–247 guidance for negotiating agreements, 250–251 legal pluralism and, 225–228 markets and, 214 marriage laws and, 220–221 mobility, 230–231 Ok Tedi agreement negotiations, 234, 240–250 property rights, 227–229 World Bank policies and, 222–225 World Bank projects and, 229–230 Women, Business, and the Law 2012, 216, 219– 220, 224, 230 Workers Party (Brazil), 295–296, 301–302 Working Group on Trade and Transfer of Technology, 91 World Bank, 84, 133, 213, 260, 262, 303–304, 343 and international organizations, 106, 110, 113 Articles of Agreement, 5–6 Ecuador Judicial Reform Project, 39 Global Forum on Law, Justice and Development, 65, 112 Integrity Vice Presidency (INT), 109 Investment Climate Advisory Service, 337, 344 Justice for the Poor program, 39–40 legal empowerment of the poor, 33, 38–41 Open Society Justice Initiative, 44 Sanctions Board, 116–117 Sanctions Board Law Digest, 117 sanctions system, 12, 101–121 and “legalism,” 106–107 and innovation, 107–110, 118 and multilateral development banks, 108, 110 and transparency, 110–121 debarment, 103–105 expansion of, 107–110 legal orientation of, 113–118 TDR program, 99 Women in Mining and Petroleum project, 240 women’s land rights and, 222–225 women’s rights and, 229–230, 232 Workshop on the Development Implications of Gender-Based Violence, 228–229 World Bank Inspection Panel, 111–112 World Development Report 2012: Gender Equality and Development, 213–214, 219 World Health Organization (WHO), 13, 94 Career Development Fellowship program, 99 World Intellectual Property Organization. see WIPO World Trade Organization (WTO), 13, 89, 91n10, 141, 179, 181–182, 185, 303, 307, 311–312 Wu Bangguo, 161nn1–2, 185 xinfang system. See China: petition system Zambia, 55 Zhang Xianzhu, 196–197 Cover Contents Foreword Preface Contributors Empowerment and Innovation Strategies for Law, Justice, and Development The Justice Innovation Approach: How Justice Sector Leaders in Development Contexts Can Promote Innovation Legal Empowerment of the Poor: Past, Present, Future Beyond the Orthodoxy of Rule of Law and Justice Sector Reform: A Framework for Legal Empowerment and Innovation through the Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities The Political Economy of Improving Traditional Justice Systems: A Case Study of NGO Engagement with Shalish in Bangladesh Intellectual Property: Facilitating Technology Transfer for Development Transforming through Transparency: Opening Up the World Bank’s Sanctions Regime Human Rights and Development: Regime Interaction and the Fragmentation of International Law Legal Transplantation and Legal Development in Transitional China Rule of Law as a Watermark: China’s Legal and Judicial Challenges Achieving Development through Innovative Constitutionalism: A China Story The Role of Laws and Institutions in Expanding Women’s Voice, Agency, and Empowerment “We Want What the Ok Tedi Women Have!” Guidance from Papua New Guinea on Women’s Engagement in Mining Deals Innovation in Asset Recovery: The Swiss Perspective International Asset Sharing: A Multipurpose Tool for Development Toward a New Law and Development: New State Activism in Brazil and the Challenge for Legal Institutions The Role of the Public Ministry in the Defense of the Environment: Hydrogeographical Regions and Attitudes for Coping with Socioenvironmental Conflicts OHADA Nears the Twenty-Year Mark: An Assessment Legal Innovation for Development: The OHADA Experience Index A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P R S T U V W X Z work_hbqvu2bdyjfrnjcicjtznrdhei ---- Good for self or good for others? The well-being benefits of kindness in two cultures depend on how the kindness is framed UC Riverside UC Riverside Previously Published Works Title Good for self or good for others? The well-being benefits of kindness in two cultures depend on how the kindness is framed Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/3g5449hf Journal JOURNAL OF POSITIVE PSYCHOLOGY, 15(6) ISSN 1743-9760 Authors Shin, Lilian J Layous, Kristin Choi, Incheol et al. Publication Date 2020-11-01 DOI 10.1080/17439760.2019.1651894 Peer reviewed eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California https://escholarship.org/uc/item/3g5449hf https://escholarship.org/uc/item/3g5449hf#author https://escholarship.org http://www.cdlib.org/ Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=rpos20 The Journal of Positive Psychology Dedicated to furthering research and promoting good practice ISSN: 1743-9760 (Print) 1743-9779 (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rpos20 Good for self or good for others? The well-being benefits of kindness in two cultures depend on how the kindness is framed Lilian J. Shin, Kristin Layous, Incheol Choi, Soojung Na & Sonja Lyubomirsky To cite this article: Lilian J. Shin, Kristin Layous, Incheol Choi, Soojung Na & Sonja Lyubomirsky (2019): Good for self or good for others? The well-being benefits of kindness in two cultures depend on how the kindness is framed, The Journal of Positive Psychology, DOI: 10.1080/17439760.2019.1651894 To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/17439760.2019.1651894 View supplementary material Published online: 14 Aug 2019. Submit your article to this journal Article views: 62 View related articles View Crossmark data https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=rpos20 https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rpos20 https://www.tandfonline.com/action/showCitFormats?doi=10.1080/17439760.2019.1651894 https://doi.org/10.1080/17439760.2019.1651894 https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/suppl/10.1080/17439760.2019.1651894 https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/suppl/10.1080/17439760.2019.1651894 https://www.tandfonline.com/action/authorSubmission?journalCode=rpos20&show=instructions https://www.tandfonline.com/action/authorSubmission?journalCode=rpos20&show=instructions https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/mlt/10.1080/17439760.2019.1651894 https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/mlt/10.1080/17439760.2019.1651894 http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1080/17439760.2019.1651894&domain=pdf&date_stamp=2019-08-14 http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1080/17439760.2019.1651894&domain=pdf&date_stamp=2019-08-14 Good for self or good for others? The well-being benefits of kindness in two cultures depend on how the kindness is framed Lilian J. Shina, Kristin Layousb, Incheol Choic, Soojung Nac* and Sonja Lyubomirskya aDepartment of Psychology, University of California, Riverside, CA, USA; bDepartment of Psychology, California State University, East Bay, Hayward, CA, USA; cDepartment of Psychology, Seoul National University, Seoul, South Korea ABSTRACT In light of cultural differences in conceptions of happiness, we investigated whether members of independent (vs. interdependent) cultures would benefit from prosocial behavior when self-focus is highlighted (vs. when other-focus is highlighted). In a 1-week randomized controlled intervention, U.S. (N = 280) and South Korean (N = 261) participants were randomly assigned to read a news article that described kind acts as good for oneself or good for others, or to read a control article. All participants then performed kind acts throughout the week, and completed pre- and post- measures of subjective well-being, connectedness, competence, and autonomy. Consistent with independent self-construals, U.S. participants who read that kindness was good for themselves showed greater increases in positive affect, satisfaction with life, and feelings of connectedness – and greater decreases in negative affect – than those who read the control article. Future research is needed to continue developing culturally-sensitive designs of positive activities. ARTICLE HISTORY Received 19 June 2019 Accepted 19 July 2019 KEYWORDS Well-being; culture; kind acts; framing; need satisfaction The pursuit of happiness is a global phenomenon, regularly dominating cultural discourse, popular media, and people’s closely held goals (Diener, 2000). Not surprisingly, psychological scientists have been exploring specific strategies – or positive activities – that can sustainably improve happiness. Positive activ- ity interventions experimentally test the practice of simple, self-administered cognitive and behavioral stra- tegies that can increase subjective well-being by pro- moting positive feelings, positive thoughts, and positive behaviors (Layous & Lyubomirsky, 2014). For example, activities such as counting one’s blessings (Chancellor, Layous, & Lyubomirsky, 2015; Emmons & McCullough, 2003; Froh, Sefick, & Emmons, 2008; Seligman, Steen, Park, & Peterson, 2005), writing letters of gratitude (Boehm, Lyubomirsky, & Sheldon, 2011; Layous, Lee, Choi, & Lyubomirsky, 2013; Layous et al., 2017; Lyubomirsky, Dickerhoof, Boehm, & Sheldon, 2011; Seligman et al., 2005), and performing acts of kindness (Chancellor, Margolis, Jacobs Bao, & Lyubomirsky, 2018; Dunn, Aknin, & Norton, 2008; Layous et al., 2013; Nelson et al., 2015; Nelson, Layous, Cole, & Lyubomirsky, 2016; Sheldon, Boehm, & Lyubomirsky, 2012) have been shown to reliably boost well-being. If administered optimally, positive activity interventions can also build positive psychological resources such as social connections and meaning in life, as well as ameliorate existing maladaptive symptoms such as anxiety and rumination (Layous, Chancellor, & Lyubomirsky, 2014; Seligman, Rashid, & Parks, 2006; Seligman et al., 2005; Shin & Lyubomirsky, 2016; Sin & Lyubomirsky, 2009; Taylor, Lyubomirsky, & Stein, 2017). A notable criticism of current research testing posi- tive activity interventions is that their trials have been conducted on primarily Anglo/European (i.e., Western) samples (Shin & Lyubomirsky, 2017; but see Layous et al., 2013; Titova, Wagstaff, & Parks, 2017, for exceptions). Because Asians comprise 60 per- cent of the world’s population (Population Reference Bureau, 2014) and Asian Americans are the fastest- growing minority group in the U.S., there is a critical need to address these groups’ mental health needs (U.S. Census, 2010). For example, South Korea cur- rently has the highest rate of hospitalizations for mental illness and the highest suicide rate for a member country of the Organization for Economic Cooperation and Development (WHO, 2017). Self- administered positive activities may be especially valuable for Asians and Asian Americans because they are relatively less stigmatizing, low-cost, and carry minimal side effects. CONTACT Lilian J. Shin LShin004@ucr.edu *Soojung Na is presently at Department of Neuroscience, Icahn School of Medicine at Mount Sinai. Supplemental data for this article can be accessed here. THE JOURNAL OF POSITIVE PSYCHOLOGY https://doi.org/10.1080/17439760.2019.1651894 © 2019 Informa UK Limited, trading as Taylor & Francis Group https://doi.org/10.1080/17439760.2019.1651894 http://www.tandfonline.com https://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1080/17439760.2019.1651894&domain=pdf&date_stamp=2019-08-13 Subjective well-being in independent versus interdependent cultures Although the need for research on strategies to improve mental health among Asians and Asian Americans is clear, investigators should be careful not to assume a one-size-fits-all approach, due to cultural differences in Western and Eastern conceptions of well-being. A widely used definition of subjective well- being in Western (independent) cultures is ‘a prepon- derance of positive affect over negative affect’ and ‘a global satisfaction with one’s life’ (Diener, 1984). In recent years, however, psychologists have sought to distinguish Eastern notions of well-being from those of Western traditions, defining interdependent subjective well-being as ‘the global, subjective assessment of whether one is interpersonally harmonized with other people, being quiescent, and being ordinary, and con- nected to the collective way of well-being’ (Hitokoto & Uchida, 2015, p. 214). These differences in conceptions of subjective well-being build upon Markus and Kitayama’s (1991) work on independent and interdependent self-construals. Markus and Kitayama (1991) define an independent self-construal as a view of the self in which Western individuals see themselves as autonomous entities who assert their rights and act agentically. In contrast, they define the Eastern, interdependent self-construal as a view of oneself as connected, relational, and belonging to a larger social group. These distinct self-views have been found to be associated with socially disengaging and socially engaging behaviors, respectively. Socially disengaging behaviors, such as asserting and protecting one’s rights, acting on the basis of one’s own judgments, and separating or distinguish- ing the self from the context, have been associated with independence and interpersonal disengage- ment of the self in the U.S. (Kitayama, Markus, & Kurokawa, 2000). Applying the concept of indepen- dent self-construal to the pursuit of happiness, sub- jective well-being in Western cultures is generally characterized by an explicit striving for one’s indivi- dual or personal happiness that may involve master- ing one’s environment and achieving goals (including social goals) independently (Uchida, Norasakkunkit, & Kitayama, 2004). In other words, with an independent approach to pursuing subjec- tive well-being, the ultimate goal is personal happi- ness, even if this pursuit may involve other people in the process. Socially engaging behavior, on the other hand, involves taking one’s proper place, perfecting one’s roles, empathizing with others, acting on the bases of others’ expectations, and blurring the distinction between self and others. This type of behavior is preva- lent in East Asian cultures and has been associated with interdependence and interpersonal engagement of the self (Kitayama et al., 2000). Subjective well-being in Eastern cultures thus emphasizes connectedness, group harmony, and the well-being of the collective group (Hitokoto & Uchida, 2015; Uchida et al., 2004) – that is, the ultimate goal is not one’s distinct personal happiness but rather the well-being of the group through harmo- nious and fulfilling relationships. As a case in point, American students’ happiness has been found to be highly correlated with interpersonally disengaged emo- tions such as pride, whereas the happiness of Japanese counterparts has been found to be more closely linked to interpersonally engaged emotions such as friendly feelings towards others (Kitayama, Mesquita, & Karasawa, 2006). Given the different approaches to well-being observed in Western and Eastern cultures, in the cur- rent study, we aimed to test whether framing a validated positive activity (i.e., doing acts of kindness) as good for the self would be additionally beneficial for increasing subjective well-being in a U.S. sample and whether framing it as good for others would be addi- tionally beneficial in a South Korean sample. In other words, by framing a traditional kindness intervention in two different ways, we sought to test cultural differ- ences in the factors that contribute to well-being. Kind acts in independent and interdependent cultures Behaving prosocially has been reliably shown to increase well-being in individuals from Western, inde- pendent cultures (Dunn et al., 2008; Layous et al., 2013; Lyubomirsky, Sheldon, Schkade, 2005; Nelson et al., 2015, 2016; Sheldon et al., 2012). Evidence is mounting, however, that remembering and enacting kindness are positive activities that have the potential to be equally successful in Eastern, interdependent cultures due to their positive focus on others (Layous et al., 2013; Nelson et al., 2015; Otake, Shimai, Tanaka- Matsumi, Otsui, & Fredrickson, 2006). For example, a study in Japan reported that people increased in subjective well-being and became more kind and grateful after counting their own kind acts over the course of 1 week (Otake et al., 2006). In another study, South Koreans showed similar increases in well-being as did Americans when performing acts of kindness (Layous et al., 2013). 2 L. J. SHIN ET AL. Additionally, self-determination theory postulates that humans have three basic needs – including auton- omy (control over one’s choices), competence (feeling that one is effective and skilled), and relatedness (i.e., connectedness; feeling close and connected to others) – and that the fulfillment of these needs is associated with greater psychological well-being (Deci & Ryan, 2000). Paralleling findings in the U.S., engaging in autonomous prosocial behavior in South Korea led to improvements in participants’ subjective well-being, as well as in feelings of autonomy, competence, and con- nectedness (Nelson et al., 2015). As a whole, these results suggest that practicing prosocial behaviors is indeed beneficial to individuals from Eastern cultures. Importantly, not all positive activities work equally well across cultures. As a case in point, when U.S. and South Korean participants were randomly assigned to express gratitude or to perform kind acts, U.S. participants benefitted from both activities, whereas South Koreans benefitted only from perform- ing kind acts but not from expressing gratitude (Layous et al., 2013). The researchers surmised that the South Koreans did not derive as much benefit from practicing gratitude because they felt indebted and/or guilty about being the recipient of others’ kind acts. This interpretation aligns with the idea that interdependent subjective well-being is concerned with the mainte- nance of interpersonal harmony, the welfare of the collective group, and the fulfillment of role obligations in relationships. Consistent with this notion, prosocial behavior may boost East Asians’ well-being by contributing to the expected norms of maintaining the well-being of the collective group. By contrast, for Western (i.e., European or North American) individuals, prosocial behavior may serve to boost well-being because it is relatively less expected and/or confirms that one is a good person. Thus, framing prosocial behavior as good for the self may enhance its ability to increase well-being among a Western sample, whereas framing it as good for others may make it more likely to increase well-being among an Eastern sample. To investigate the idea that members of indepen- dent cultures benefit from prosocial behavior when self-focus is highlighted, whereas members of interde- pendent cultures benefit when other-focus is high- lighted, we designed a 1-week randomized controlled intervention. Participants from the U.S. (independent culture) and South Korea (interdependent culture) were randomly assigned to read a news article that described kind acts as good for oneself or good for others, or to read a control article about the benefits of being organized. All participants were then asked to perform kind acts throughout the week and completed both baseline and post-intervention measures of sub- jective well-being, connectedness, competence, and autonomy. Hypotheses First, we predicted that, due to their independent orien- tation, U.S. participants who read that performing kind acts is good for themselves (i.e., with ‘good for self’ framing) and then perform them would experience greater gains in subjective well-being (namely, increased positive affect, decreased negative affect, and increased life satisfaction), as well as in autonomy, competence, and connectedness, than those who per- form kind acts without any framing (i.e., controls; Hypothesis 1). In contrast, we hypothesized that, due to their inter- dependent orientation, South Koreans who read that kind acts are good for others (i.e., ‘good for others’ framing) and perform them would experience larger improvements in subjective well-being and need satis- faction than controls (i.e., no framing; Hypothesis 2). Method Participants Two samples of students were recruited for this study. The first group comprised undergraduates (n = 309) attending the University of California, Riverside (UCR) – a diverse, large public university in the United States – who completed the study in exchange for course credit. In this group, 29 participants were removed from the sample because they failed to complete the second time point, leaving a total of 280 participants (67% female), ages 18 to 35 (Mage = 19.2, SD = 1.65). Fifty-two percent of participants were Asian/Asian American, 28% Hispanic/Latino(a), 7% White/Caucasian, 3% Black/ African American, and 10% Other/More than one (see Discussion on implications of ethnic identification of U.S. participants). A chi-square test of independence revealed that the participants who failed to complete the second time point did not vary by condition from those who did complete it, χ2 (2, N = 309) = 1.83, p = .40. Drop-out status was examined as a predictor of all of our dependent variables, but no significant differences were found between U.S. participants who remained in the study until the end and those who dropped out after the first timepoint (all ts(307) < |.81|; all ps > .42). Final sample sizes per condition in the U.S. were as follows: Good for Self (n = 112), Good for Others (n = 87), and Control (n = 81). A statistical power THE JOURNAL OF POSITIVE PSYCHOLOGY 3 analysis software program, G*Power 3.1, revealed that for a small effect size (f = .16) and an alpha value of .05, 280 participants in three groups could detect the effect with 79% power (Faul, ErdFelder, Lang, & Buchner, 2007). Chi-square tests of independence indicated that gender, χ2 (4, N = 279) = 4.37, p = .36, and ethnicity, χ2 (12, N = 279) = 11.16, p = .52, did not vary by condition for the U.S. participants. The second group comprised undergraduates (n = 340) attending Seoul National University (SNU) – a large public university in South Korea – who also completed the study in exchange for course credit. In this group, 67 participants were removed for not com- pleting the second time point, leaving a total of 273 participants (48% female; 99% Korean, 1% other), ages 18 to 30 (Mage = 21.4, SD = 2.63). A chi-square test of independence revealed that the participants who dropped out did not vary by condition from the parti- cipants who completed, χ2 (2, N = 340) = 2.85, p = .24. Drop-out status did not significantly predict any of our dependent variables (all ts(338) < |1.09|; all ps > .28). Sample sizes per condition in S. Korea were as fol- lows: Good for Self (n = 88), Good for Others (n = 91), and Control (n = 94). For an alpha value of .05, 273 participants in 3 groups can detect a small effect size (f = .16) with 78% power. Finally, neither gender, χ2 (2, N = 273) = 3.31, p = .19, nor ethnicity, χ2 (2, N = 273) = 2.01, p = .37, varied by condition for South Korean participants. Design and procedure A 3 (Condition: Good for Self, Good for Others, Control) × 2 (Cultural Background: U.S., South Korea) × 2 (Time: baseline/pre-intervention, post-intervention) mixed fac- torial design was used in this study (see Figure 1 for study timeline and measures). At baseline, all participants completed demographics and several well-being measures (described below). All measures and intervention instructions were adminis- tered in English for U.S. participants and in Korean for South Korean participants. To create the Korean mea- sures and intervention instructions, the English mea- sures and instructions were translated into Korean by a bilingual speaker and then back-translated into English in order to confirm that the translations con- tained the same content as the English measures and instructions. Participants were then randomly assigned to read news articles – all ostensibly from TIME Magazine for U.S. participants and Naver News for S. Korean partici- pants – about how kindness benefits the self (Good for Self condition), how kindness benefits others (Good for Others condition), or how being organized benefits the self (neutral Control condition).1 As shown in Appendices A and D, the Good for Self group read about evidence that being kind can increase personal happiness, alleviate depression, and boost work productivity, and that these effects occur universally across many cultures. Participants in the Good for Others group read about how being kind can boost the positive emotions, self- esteem, feelings of connectedness, engagement at work, and health of the recipients of kindness, and that these effects are evident across many different cultures (see Appendices B and E). Finally, the Control group read about how organizational skills can increase efficiency, the management of responsibilities, and the attainment of personal goals (see Appendices C and F). After reading their assigned article, all participants were asked to perform acts of kindness for others. They could perform as many kind acts as they wanted, to whomever they chose, and with or with- out the beneficiary’s awareness; the only stipulation was that they were to be performed in all in one day. The instructions were as follows: Complete: Demographics, Positive and Negative Affect, Life Satisfaction, Psychological Needs Read: News Article* Complete: Report Kind Acts, Positive and Negative Affect, Life Satisfaction, Psychological Needs Perform Kind Acts BASELINE Day 1 POST-TEST Day 8 Figure 1. Study timeline and measures. *News Article Conditions: 1) Kindness is good for the self, 2) Kindness is good for others, or 3) Organization is good (control group) 4 L. J. SHIN ET AL. In our daily lives, we all perform acts of kindness for others. These acts may be large or small and the person for whom the act is performed may or may not be aware of the act. Examples include helping your par- ents cook dinner, doing a chore for your sister or brother, helping a friend with homework, visiting an elderly relative, or writing a thank you letter. During one day this week (any day you choose), you are to perform acts of kindness (as many as you want) – all in one day. The acts do not need to be for the same person, the person may or may not be aware of the act, and the act may or may not be similar to the acts listed above. Next week, you will report what acts of kindness you chose to perform. Please do not perform any acts that may place yourself or others in danger. After 1 week, participants logged back into the survey website, reported the kind acts they had performed that week, and completed post-manipulation measures of all of the constructs assessed at baseline. Measures Positive and negative affect Participants’ emotions were assessed using the Modified Differential Emotions Scale (mDES; Fredrickson, Tugade, Waugh, & Larkin, 2003). The mDES requires participants to recall and rate their strongest experience of a variety of positive emotions (e.g. ‘I have felt amused, fun-loving, silly’) and negative emotions (e.g. ‘I have felt angry, irritated, annoyed’) during the past week on a 5-point scale (0 = never, 5 = all of the time). The mDES includes a subscale for positive emotions (e.g., amusement, compassion, con- fidence; Cronbach’s α = .87 at baseline; α = .88 at post- intervention) and a subscale for negative emotions (e.g., anger, sadness, contempt; α = .85 at baseline; α = .88 at post-intervention). Life satisfaction To assess life satisfaction, participants completed the Satisfaction With Life Scale (SWLS; Diener, Emmons, Larsen, & Griffin, 1985). The SWLS consists of five items (e.g., ‘In most ways my life is close to my ideal’) rated on a 7-point scale (1 = strongly disagree, 7 = strongly agree). Cronbach’s α coefficients were .85 at baseline and .85 at post-intervention. Psychological need satisfaction Rooted in self-determination theory (Deci & Ryan, 2000), psychological need satisfaction assesses the degree to which people’s core needs are being met (Sheldon, Elliot, Kim, & Kasser, 2001; Sheldon & Hilpert, 2012). The Balanced Measure of Psychological Needs consists of 18 items, with six each representing autonomy (e.g. ‘I felt free to do things my own way’), connectedness (e.g. ‘I felt a sense of contact with people who care for me, and whom I care for’), and competence (e.g. ‘I felt that I was taking on and mastering hard challenges’ (1 = no agreement, 5 = much agreement; Sheldon et al., 2001). Due to relatively low reliability (α = .58 to .67) of the three types of need satisfaction, results were analyzed by examining the three positively-worded items only (and excluding the three reverse-scored items).2 Studies have suggested that reverse-scored items tend to load onto a separate factor than positively-worded items, compromising the scale’s validity (Gehlbach, 2015). For positively-worded connectedness items, α = .80 at baseline and α = .76 at post-intervention; for positively-worded competence items, α = .81 at baseline and α = .83 at post- intervention; for positively-worded autonomy items, α = .67 at baseline and α = .69 at post-intervention. Because the reliability of positively-worded autonomy items was still low, autonomy was removed when we analyzed the data. Acculturation To assess level of acculturation, Asian and Asian American participants in the U.S. completed a short version of the Suinn-Lew Asian Self Identity Acculturation scale (SL-ASIA; Suinn, Ahuna, & Khoo, 1992). The SL-ASIA consisted of 11 items (e.g., ‘Whom do you now associate with in the community?’) rated on a 5-point scale (1 = Almost exclusively Asians, Asian- Americans, Orientals, 5 = Almost exclusively Anglos, Black, Hispanics, or other non-Asian ethnic groups). An average was computed, with higher scores on this measure indicating greater acculturation. Cronbach’s α coeffi- cient was .80. Results Preliminary analyses We split the data by culture and analyzed participants’ baseline levels of all dependent variables for significant differences among conditions. (See Tables 1 and 2 for baseline and posttest means of all dependent vari- ables.) No differences were found. However, when we explored baseline differences by culture, collapsing across conditions, we found that the U.S. participants started with much higher baseline scores in positive affect, F(1, 643) = 65.71, p < .001, life satisfaction, F(1, 643) = 19.83, p < .001, connectedness, F(1, 643) = 12.66, p < .001, and competence, F(1, 643) = 12.85, p < .001. Because Americans and Koreans seemed to fundamen- tally differ in their initial subjective well-being and need satisfaction, we decided to analyze our results sepa- rately by culture. THE JOURNAL OF POSITIVE PSYCHOLOGY 5 Manipulation check To ensure that the framing kindness articles were dif- ferent in the ways that we intended (e.g. vis-à-vis their implied benefits to self vs. others), we asked indepen- dent raters to judge the English and Korean articles for the number of good-for-others benefits and the num- ber of good-for-self benefits. ICCs for the English and Korean raters ranged from .69 to .98 for the 3 articles, which are considered good to excellent reliabilities (Fleiss, 1986). As intended, in both the English and Korean articles, more good-for-self benefits (M = 7.00 and M = 6.33 for English and Korean, respectively) than good-for-others benefits (M = 0.67; M = 2.00) were counted in the good-for-self article; more good-for- others benefits (M = 6.67; M = 6.00) than good-for-self benefits (M = 1.00; M = 4.00) were counted in the good- for-others article; and, finally, more good-for-self bene- fits (M = 6.33; M = 10.33) than good-for-others benefits (M = 0.00; M = 0.00) were counted in the control article. Changes in subjective well-being, connectedness, and competence Using the data set combined from both cultures, we also examined whether any dependent variables dif- fered as a function of time, condition, and culture. The F-test for the Time X Condition X Culture inter- action was significant for life satisfaction, F(2, 547) = 4.51, p = .01, and connectedness F(2, 547) = 3.27, p = .04. However, in view of our hypotheses, we were most interested in the planned contrast analyses reported below. United States To test Hypothesis 1, we first calculated difference scores by subtracting Time 1 from Time 2 dependent variables – namely, positive emotions, negative emotions, life satis- faction, connectedness, and competence.3 We then con- ducted planned contrasts on these difference scores to compare the Good for Self (+1), Good for Others (0), and Control (−1) conditions in both the U.S. and South Korean groups. The results of these analyses are shown in Table 1 and Figures 2 and 3. In support of Hypothesis 1, U.S. students who read that kindness was good for themselves showed greater increases in positive affect, tcontrast(277) = 3.25, p = .001, satisfaction with life, tcontrast (277) = 2.80, p = .01, feelings of connectedness, tcontrast (277) = 2.58, p = .01, and greater decreases in negative affect, tcontrast(277) = −2.19, p = .03, than those who read that organization was good (control). No differences were found between conditions in the U.S. for compe- tence, tcontrast(277) = .55, p = .58. Notably, our U.S. sample included students from diverse backgrounds, including members of interde- pendent cultures, limiting the validity of the com- parisons we could make to Asian students in Asia. In fact, only 7% of our sample identified as White/ Caucasian, the prototypical race/ethnicity associated with individualism, whereas 52% identified as Asian/ Asian American and 28% as Hispanic/Latino(a) – ethnic groups that have interdependent cultural Table 1. Cell means (Standard Deviations) and results of planned contrast analyses on U.S. Sample. Self (+1) Other (0) Control (−1) Dependent variable Time 1 M (SD) Time 2 M (SD) Time 1 M (SD) Time 2 M (SD) Time 1 M (SD) Time 2 M (SD) t (df) p Well-being Positive affect (mDES) 3.33 (0.65) 3.46 (0.62) 3.45 (0.66) 3.44 (0.75) 3.42 (0.64) 3.26 (0.76) 3.25 (277) 0.001** Negative affect (mDES) 2.24 (0.72) 2.12 (0.79) 2.32 (0.74) 2.22 (0.79) 2.14 (0.65) 2.23 (0.81) −2.19 (277) 0.03* Satisfaction With Life 4.46 (1.16) 4.68 (1.22) 4.56 (1.29) 4.49 (1.23) 4.83 (1.20) 4.66 (1.22) 2.80 (277) 0.01* Need Satisfaction Connectedness 3.77 (0.77) 3.82 (0.76) 3.78 (0.83) 3.75 (0.86) 3.88 (0.87) 3.58 (0.85) 2.58 (277) 0.01* Competence 2.99 (0.86) 3.15 (0.82) 3.05 (0.96) 3.10 (0.88) 3.23 (0.91) 3.28 (0.96) 0.55 (277) 0.58 Note. *p < .05. ** p < .01. Table 2. Cell Means (Standard Deviations) and results of planned contrast analyses on south korean sample. Self (0) Other (+1) Control (−1) Dependent variable Time 1 M (SD) Time 2 M (SD) Time 1 M (SD) Time 2 M (SD) Time 1 M (SD) Time 2 M (SD) t (df) p Well-being Positive affect (mDES) 2.92 (0.67) 3.03 (0.66) 3.02 (0.60) 3.00 (0.59) 3.03 (0.63) 3.09 (0.58) −0.28 (270) 0.78 Negative affect (mDES) 2.40 (0.73) 2.28 (0.85) 2.26 (0.75) 2.20 (0.72) 2.28 (0.72) 2.30 (0.76) −1.28 (270) 0.20 Satisfaction With Life 4.11 (1.14) 4.12 (1.10) 4.26 (1.07) 4.24 (1.14) 4.26 (1.08) 4.47 (1.07) −1.04 (270) 0.30 Need Satisfaction Connectedness 3.47 (0.79) 3.55 (0.71) 3.63 (0.72) 3.46 (0.77) 3.58 (0.82) 3.57 (0.84) −1.35 (270) 0.18 Competence 2.71 (0.91) 2.79 (0.93) 2.85 (0.91) 2.89 (0.88) 2.82 (0.84) 2.78 (0.91) 0.79 (270) 0.43 Note. *p < .05. ** p < .01. 6 L. J. SHIN ET AL. roots (Schwartz, 2007; Shin & Lyubomirsky, 2016). To address this sample characteristic, we ran the ana- lyses exclusively with Asian Americans and found that the Asian Americans in our U.S. sample responded more similarly to the U.S. sample than they did to the South Korean sample. The only variable on which Asian Americans differed from the U.S. sample as whole – albeit marginally – was negative affect, tcontrast(142) = 2.39, p = .09. The other variables showed a similar pattern of effects as the U.S. sample as a whole. Additionally, the mean acculturation level of our Asian American participants was above the midpoint (3.07 on a 5-point scale), indicating that many of them identified at least to a moderate degree with American culture. We conducted regression analyses using acculturation level as a moderator and found that none of the outcome variables were affected by the acculturation level of the Asian Americans. These results support our rationale for using the U.S. participants as our independent cultural sample, despite the high proportion of Asian Americans in the sample. Nevertheless, to provide a sharper contrast to participants residing in Asia, future investigations should aim to include more Western-residing partici- pants with Anglo or European roots. South Korea We conducted parallel analyses (using the following contrast weights: Good for Others [+1], Good for Self [0], and control [−1]) to test Hypothesis 2; the results are shown in Table 2 and Figures 2 and 3. Failing to provide support for this hypothesis, South Korean stu- dents who read that kindness was good for others did Changes in Negative Affect US SK -0.4 -0.3 -0.2 -0.1 0 0.1 0.2 0.3 0.4 N eg at iv e A ffe ct ( m D E S ) Self Other Control Changes in Positive Affect US SK -0.4 -0.3 -0.2 -0.1 0 0.1 0.2 0.3 0.4 P os iti ve A ffe ct ( m D E S ) Self Other Control Changes in Satisfaction With Life US SK -0.4 -0.3 -0.2 -0.1 0 0.1 0.2 0.3 0.4 S at is fa ct io n W ith L ife Self Other Control The Journal of Positive Psychology Figure 2. Changes in subjective well-being for the Self, Other, and Control conditions in the U.S. and South Korea. Note. US = United States, SK = South Korea. Self = Good-for-Self framing, Other = Good-for-Other framing, Control = Organization is good framing. Data represent THE JOURNAL OF POSITIVE PSYCHOLOGY 7 not show greater increases in positive affect, life satis- faction, connectedness, or competence – or decreases in negative affect – compared to those in the control group (all tcontrasts < |1.35|; all ps > .18). Discussion This study tested whether individuals from indepen- dent cultures would benefit in subjective well-being, connectedness, and competence when self-related rewards of prosocial behavior are underscored, while those from interdependent cultures would benefit when other-related rewards are underscored. Summary of findings Supporting Hypothesis 1, U.S. participants who per- formed acts of kindness after reading that they were good for ‘them’ reported greater increases in positive affect, life satisfaction, and connectedness, as well as decreases in negative affect, than those who performed kind acts after reading a neutral framing. The article content may have helped explicate to individualists that they should be motivated to be prosocial because it could be a vehicle for the explicit pursuit of their happiness and also boost their self-esteem. Our results are consistent with the concept of independent subjective well-being, in that members of individualist cultures may benefit from prosocial behavior when it is explicitly framed as a way by which to pursue their personal happiness (Uchida et al., 2004). Another pos- sibility is that the benefits of kindness for others are obvious, so reading an article that frames kindness as good for others was not additionally motivating com- pared to reading an article that frames kindness as good for oneself. Indeed, these results provide addi- tional evidence in support of the existing research that prosocial behavior is an effective way to increase well-being in individualist cultures (Dunn et al., 2008; Layous et al., 2013; Lyubomirsky et al., 2005; Nelson et al., 2015, 2016; Sheldon et al., 2012). Our study, however, failed to support Hypothesis 2 for any of the outcome variables – namely, South Korean students who performed acts of kindness after reading that they were good for others did not increase in well-being, connectedness, and competence com- pared to those who performed acts of kindness after reading the neutral framing. Perhaps South Koreans do not experience additional gains in well-being from con- sidering kind acts as good for others (vs. performing them without reasons/framing) because, due to their interdependent values, the benefits to others are obvious and pointing them out does not provide any further advantage (Markus & Kitayama, 1991). Another Changes in Connectedness US SK -0.4 -0.3 -0.2 -0.1 0 0.1 0.2 0.3 0.4 C o n n e ct e d n e ss Self Other Control Figure 3. Changes in connectedness and competence for the Self, Other, and Control conditions in the U.S. and South Korea. Note. US = United States, SK = South Korea. Self = Good-for-Self framing, Other = Good-for-Other framing, Control = Organization is good framing. Data represent 8 L. J. SHIN ET AL. possible explanation is that the Good-for-Others article presented the benefits of doing kind acts for others’ individual well-being, rather than their benefits to inter- dependent well-being, such as group harmony. To bet- ter appeal to the concepts of well-being shared by members of interdependent cultures, future studies that manipulate the framing of positive activities for collectivist cultures might consider incorporating the benefits for in-group relationships and the group as a whole. Additionally, framing kindness as good for others for South Koreans – especially within close rela- tionships – may not be useful, because it might signal to them that those relationships are distant (Zhang, Li, Bai & Li, 2018). Finally, we may not have found signifi- cant well-being differences in South Korea (but did in the U.S.) because research shows that Americans tend to use more ‘extreme’ (e.g., never or always) responses on rating scales, whereas Koreans, with their preference for low-arousal emotions, are more likely to select answer choices in the middle or neutral point of the scale (Chen, Lee, & Stevenson, 1995; Mayer, Elliot, Haas, Hays, & Weinick, 2016). Limitations and future directions A limitation of our study was that we measured the individual well-being of our American and South Korean participants rather than their interdependent well-being. Hence, we may not have measured what South Koreans actually value as well-being or happi- ness. To assess interdependent subjective well-being from an emic approach, future investigators could incorporate a measure like the Interdependent Happiness Scale (IHS), which has been designed and validated in both Western and Eastern countries (Hitokoto & Uchida, 2015). This scale is designed to answer the questions, ‘Are we happy or not?’ or ‘Am I making others happy?’ rather than ‘Am I happy?’ By incorporating the IHS or similar measures, future researchers may be able to capture not only the happi- ness of individual participants, but also their experi- ences of group harmony and collective well-being, which are critical to the experience of interdependent subjective well-being. Despite this limitation, there is evidence that the IHS is strongly positively correlated with life satisfaction (r = .61) and positive affect (r = .61) and negatively correlated with negative affect (r = −.60), which were measured as outcomes in our study (Hitokoto & Uchida, 2015). Similarly, because collectivists value the appraisal of their lives by close others (Suh, Diener, & Updegraff, 2008), future investigators may wish to consider using alternative measures of life satisfaction that include asking collectivist participants how close others (e.g., family members) would evaluate their lives instead of merely asking how they themselves evaluate their own lives (as we did in the current study). Furthermore, it has also been suggested that researchers who study emotions in members of Asian cultures inquire about psychosomatic symptoms, which might allow Asians to convey their emotions indirectly and thus minimize disruption to relational harmony (Shin & Lyubomirsky, 2016; e.g., see the literature on somatization: Hong, Lee, & Lorenzo, 1995; Kleinman, 1982; Park & Bernstein, 2008; Parker, Cheah, & Roy, 2001; Zhou et al., 2015). Finally, although all three U.S. groups performed kind acts, the control group, which read about the benefits of being organized, displayed decreases in positive affect, satisfaction with life, and connectedness. We found it interesting that these control participants decreased in subjective well-being even after perform- ing kind acts; perhaps, this occurred as a result of a mismatch between what they were led to believe was good for them (organization) and the task they were asked to carry out (kind acts). South Koreans, however, may not have been as affected by this mis- match due to their patterns of dialectical thought and/ or respect for authority (Lu & Gilmour, 2004). To further unpack these results, future research could include comparison conditions with alternative ways of framing kind acts, such as a more neutral control article about kind acts (but not their benefits), or no framing at all. Finally, our U.S. participants who read that organization was good (and subsequently performed kind acts) did not show any differences in competence from partici- pants who learned that kindness is good for the self. We speculate that students who read that organization is helpful may have practiced more organizational skills in addition to kind acts during the intervention period, which, in turn, may have helped maintain their sense of competence. Concluding words The present study contributes to the sparse body of research about subjective well-being in independent versus interdependent cultures. Our results are consis- tent with the notion that Americans appear to value THE JOURNAL OF POSITIVE PSYCHOLOGY 9 independent subjective well-being, while raising ques- tions about what interdependent subjective well-being looks like in modern South Korea. With mental health concerns on the rise in Asian countries, we urge researchers to investigate the optimal design and implementation of positive activity interventions in interdependent cultures. Notes 1. Prior to the current study, we conducted a similar study in which participants read news articles about how happiness is good for the self, how happiness is good for others, or about how being organized was benefi- cial and found no significant differences between these framing conditions for any of the outcome variables, PA, NA, SWL, Connectedness, and Competence (all tcontrasts < |1.78|; all ps > .05). 2. For negatively-worded connectedness items, α = .44 at baseline and α = .43 at post-intervention; for nega- tively-worded competence items, α = .60 at baseline and α = .70 at post-intervention; for negatively-worded autonomy items, α = .57 at baseline and α = .63 at post- intervention. 3. Standardized difference score contrasts (Time 1 was standardized by Time 1 SDs and Time 2 was standar- dized by Time 2 SDs) produced the same (significant) results as the unstandardized contrasts reported in this paper. Disclosure statement No potential conflict of interest was reported by the authors. References Boehm, J. K., Lyubomirsky, S., & Sheldon, K. M. (2011). A longitudinal experimental study comparing the effective- ness of happiness-enhancing strategies in Anglo Americans and Asian Americans. Cognition & Emotion, 25(7), 1263–1272. Chancellor, J., Layous, K., & Lyubomirsky, S. (2015). Recalling positive events at work makes employees feel happier, move more, but interact less: A 6-week randomized con- trolled intervention at a Japanese workplace. Journal of Happiness Studies, 16(4), 871–887. Chancellor, J., Margolis, S. M., Jacobs Bao, K., & Lyubomirsky, S. (2018). Everyday prosociality in the workplace: The benefits of giving, getting, and glimpsing. Emotion, 18(4), 507–517. Chen, C., Lee, S., & Stevenson, H. W. (1995). Response style and cross-cultural comparisons of rating scales among East Asian and North American students. Psychological Science, 6(3), 170–175. Deci, E. L., & Ryan, R. M. (2000). Self-determination theory and the facilitation of intrinsic motivation, social development, and well-being. American Psychologist, 55(1), 68–78. Diener, E. (1984). Subjective well-being. Psychological Bulletin, 95(3), 542–575. Diener, E. (2000). Subjective well-being: The science of happi- ness and a proposal for a national index. American Psychologist, 55(1), 34–43. Diener, E., Emmons, R. A., Larsen, R. J., & Griffin, S. (1985). The satisfaction with life scale. Journal of Personality Assessment, 49(1), 71–75. Dunn, E. W., Aknin, L. B., & Norton, M. I. (2008). Spending money on others promotes happiness. Science, 319(5870), 1687–1688. Emmons, R. A., & McCullough, M. E. (2003). Counting blessings versus burdens: An experimental investigation of gratitude and subjective well-being in daily life. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 84, 377–389. Faul, F., ErdFelder, E., Lang, A.-G., & Buchner, A. (2007). G*Power 3.1 manual. Behavioral Research Methods, 39(2), 175–191. Fleiss, J. L. (1986). The design and analysis of clinical experi- ments. New York: John Wiley & Sons. Fredrickson, B. L., Tugade, M. M., Waugh, C. E., & Larkin, G. (2003). What good are positive emotions in crises? A prospective study of resilience and emotions follow- ing the terrorist attacks on the United States on September 11th, 2001. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 84, 365–376. Froh, J. J., Sefick, W. J., & Emmons, R. A. (2008). Counting blessings in early adolescents: An experimental study of gratitude and subjective well-being. Journal of School Psychology, 46(2), 213–233. Gehlbach, H. (2015). Seven survey sins. Journal of Early Adolescence, 35(5–6), 883–897. Hitokoto, H., & Uchida, Y. (2015). Interdependent happiness: Theoretical importance and measurement validity. Journal of Happiness Studies, 16, 211–239. Hong, G. K., Lee, B. S., & Lorenzo, M. K. (1995). Somatization in Chinese American clients: Implications for psychotherapeu- tic services. Journal of Contemporary Psychotherapy, 25(2), 105–118. Kitayama, S., Markus, H. R., & Kurokawa, M. (2000). Culture, emotion, and well-being: Good feelings in Japan and the United States. Cognition and Emotion, 14(1), 93–124. Kitayama, S., Mesquita, B., & Karasawa, M. (2006). Cultural affordances and emotional experience: Socially engaging and disengaging emotions in Japan and the United States. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 91(5), 890–903. Kleinman, A. (1982). Neurasthenia and depression: A study of somatization and culture in China. Culture, Medicine and Psychiatry, 6(2), 117–190. Layous, K., & Lyubomirsky, S. (2014). The how, why, what, when, and who of happiness: Mechanisms underlying the success of positive interventions. In J. Gruber & J. T. Moscowitz (Eds.), Positive emotion: Integrating the light sides and dark sides (pp. 473–495). New York: Oxford University Press. Layous, K., Chancellor, J., & Lyubomirsky, S. (2014). Positive activities as protective factors against mental health conditions. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 123(1), 3–12. Layous, K., Lee, H., Choi, I., & Lyubomirsky, S. (2013). Culture matters when designing a successful happiness-increasing 10 L. J. SHIN ET AL. activity: A comparison of the United States and South Korea. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology, 44, 1294–1303. Layous, K., Sweeny, K., Armenta, C. N., Na, S., Choi, I., & Lyubomirsky, S. (2017). The proximal experience of gratitude. Plos One, 12(7), e0179123. Lu, L., & Gilmore, R. (2004). Culture and conceptions of happi- ness: Individual oriented and social oriented SWB. Journal of Happiness Studies, 5(3), 269–291. Lyubomirsky, S., Dickerhoof, R., Boehm, J. K., & Sheldon, K. M. (2011). Becoming happier takes both a will and a proper way: An experimental longitudinal intervention to boost well-being. Emotion, 11(2), 391–402. Lyubomirsky, S., Sheldon, K. M., & Schkade, D. (2005). Pursuing happiness: The architecture of sustainable change. Review of General Psychology, 9(2), 111–131. Markus, H. R., & Kitayama, S. (1991). Culture and the self: Implications for cognition, emotion, and motivation. Psychological Review, 98(2), 224–253. Mayer, L. A., Elliott, M. N., Haas, A., Hays, R. D., & Weinick, R. M. (2016). Less use of extreme response options by Asians to standardized care scenarios may explain some racial/ethnic differences in CAHPS scores. Medical Care, 54(1), 38–44. Nelson, S. K., Della Porta, M. D., Jacobs Bao, K., Lee, H. C., Choi, I., & Lyubomirsky, S. (2015). ‘It’s up to you’: Experimentally manipulated autonomy support for proso- cial behavior improves well-being in two cultures over six weeks. The Journal of Positive Psychology, 10, 463–476. Nelson, S. K., Layous, K., Cole, S., & Lyubomirsky, S. (2016). Do unto others or treat yourself?: The effects of prosocial and self-focused behavior on psychological flourishing. Emotion, 16(6), 850–861. Otake, K., Shimai, S., Tanaka-Matsumi, J., Otsui, K., & Fredrickson, B. L. (2006). Happy people become happier through kindness: A counting kindnesses intervention. Journal of Happiness Studies, 7(3), 361–375. Park, S.-Y., & Bernstein, K. S. (2008). Depression and Korean American immigrants. Archives of Psychiatric Nursing, 22(1), 12–19. Parker, G., Cheah, Y.-C., & Roy, K. (2001). Do the Chinese somatize depression? A cross-cultural study. Social Psychiatry and Psychiatric Epidemiology, 36(6), 287–293. Population Reference Bureau (2014). 2014 world population data sheet. Retrieved from http://www.prb.org/pdf14/2014- world-population-data-sheet_eng.pdf Schwartz, S. J. (2007). The applicability of familism to diverse ethnic groups: A preliminary study. The Journal of Social Psychology, 147(2), 101–118. Seligman, M. E. P., Rashid, T., & Parks, A. C. (2006). Positive psychotherapy. American Psychologist, 61(8), 774–788. Seligman, M. E. P., Steen, T. A., Park, N., & Peterson, C. (2005). Positive psychology progress: Empirical validation of interventions. American Psychologist, 60(5), 410–421. Sheldon, K. M., Boehm, J. K., & Lyubomirsky, S. (2012). Variety is the spice of happiness: The hedonic adaptation preven- tion (HAP) model. In I. Boniwell & S. David (Eds.), Oxford handbook of happiness (pp. 901–914). Oxford: Oxford University Press. Sheldon, K. M., Elliot, A. J., Kim, Y., & Kasser, T. (2001). What is satisfying about satisfying events? Testing 10 candidate psychological needs. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 80(2), 25–339. Sheldon, K. M., & Hilpert, J. C. (2012). The Balanced Measure of Psychological Needs (BMPN) scale: An alternative domain general measure of need satisfaction. Motivation and Emotion, 36(4), 439–451. Shin, L. J., & Lyubomirsky, S. (2016). Positive activity interven- tions for mental health conditions: Basic research and clin- ical applications. In J. Johnson & A. Wood (Eds.), The handbook of positive clinical psychology (pp. 349–363). New York: Wiley. Shin, L. J, & Lyubomirsky, S. (2017). Positive activity interven- tions for interdependent cultures. In S. Donaldson & M. Rao (Eds.), Scientific advances in positive psychology (pp. 11–36). Santa Barbara, CA: Praeger. Sin, N. L., & Lyubomirsky, S. (2009). Enhancing well-being and alleviating depressive symptoms with positive psychology interventions: A practice-friendly meta-analysis. Journal of Clinical Psychology, 65(5), 467–487. Suh, E. M., Diener, E., & Updegraff, J. A. (2008). From culture to priming conditions: Self-construal influences on life satis- faction judgments. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology, 39 (1), 3–15. Suinn, R. M., Ahuna, C., & Khoo, G. (1992). The suinn-lew asian self-identity acculturation scale: Concurrent and factorial validation. Educational and Psychological Measurement, 52 (4), 1041–1046. doi:10.1177/0013164492052004028 Taylor, C. T., Lyubomirsky, S., & Stein, M. B. (2017). Upregulating the positive affect system in anxiety and depression: Outcomes of a positive activity intervention. Depression and Anxiety, 34, 267–280. Titova, L., Wagstaff, A. E., & Parks, A. C. (2017). Disentangling the effects of gratitude and optimism: A cross-cultural investigation. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology, 48(5), 754–770. U.S. Census Bureau. (2010). Overview of race and Hispanic origin: 2010. Retrieved from http://www.census.gov/prod/ cen2010/briefs/c2010br-02.pdf Uchida, Y., Norasakkunkit, V., & Kitayama, S. (2004). Cultural constructions of happiness: Theory and empirical evidence. Journal of Happiness Studies, 5, 223–239. World Health Organization. (2017). Suicide rates, age-standardized data by country. Retrieved from http:// apps.who.int/gho/data/node.main.MHSUICIDEASDR?lang= en Zhang, N., Ji, L. J., Bai, B., & Li, Y. (2018). Culturally divergent consequences of receiving thanks in close relationships. Emotion, 18(1), 46–57. Zhou, X., Min, S., Sun, J., Kim, S. J., Ahn, J., Peng, Y., . . . Ryder, A. G. (2015). Extending a structural model of somatization to South Koreans: Cultural values, somati- zation tendency, and the presentation of depressive symptoms. Journal of Affective Disorders, 176, 151–154. THE JOURNAL OF POSITIVE PSYCHOLOGY 11 http://www.prb.org/pdf14/2014-world-population-data-sheet_eng.pdf http://www.prb.org/pdf14/2014-world-population-data-sheet_eng.pdf https://doi.org/10.1177/0013164492052004028 http://www.census.gov/prod/cen2010/briefs/c2010br-02.pdf http://www.census.gov/prod/cen2010/briefs/c2010br-02.pdf http://apps.who.int/gho/data/node.main.MHSUICIDEASDR?lang=en http://apps.who.int/gho/data/node.main.MHSUICIDEASDR?lang=en http://apps.who.int/gho/data/node.main.MHSUICIDEASDR?lang=en Abstract Subjective well-being in independent versus interdependent cultures Kind acts in independent and interdependent cultures Hypotheses Method Participants Design and procedure Measures Positive and negative affect Life satisfaction Psychological need satisfaction Acculturation Results Preliminary analyses Manipulation check Changes in subjective well-being, connectedness, and competence United States South Korea Discussion Summary of findings Limitations and future directions Concluding words Notes Disclosure statement References work_hcnznfhsajhglkf47tfoslnhea ---- Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 U.S. Department of Justice Office of Justice Programs Bureau of Justice Statistics BJS Mandatory P.L. 280 states Optional P.L. 280 states Indian reservations (U.S. Census Bureau) Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics Overview Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities Duren Banks, Steven W. Perry, and Allina Lee Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 Brian Reaves State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 Steven W. Perry, Ron Malega, and Duren Banks Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 Todd Minton Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System Mark Motivans and Howard Snyder Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 2 June 2011 Bureau of Justice Statistics James P. Lynch Director BJS Website: www.bjs.gov For information contact: BJS Clearinghouse 1-800-732-3277 The Bureau of Justice Statistics is the statistics agency of the U.S. Department of Justice. Duren Banks coordinated the development of this compendium. Contributing authors include Duren Banks, Allina Lee, Ron Malega, Todd Minton, Mark Motivans, Steven W. Perry, Brian Reaves, and Howard Snyder. In addition to the authors, other BJS staff who contributed to verification include Paul Guerino, Tracey Kyckelhahn, and Tracy L. Snell. Morgan Young and Jill Thomas edited the report, Barbara Quinn designed and produced the report, and Jayne Robinson and Tina Dorsey prepared the report for final printing under the supervision of Doris J. James. June 2011, NCJ 234459 3Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 BJS Mandatory P.L. 280 states Optional P.L. 280 states Indian reservations (U.S. Census Bureau) Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics Overview Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities Duren Banks, Steven W. Perry, and Allina Lee Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 Brian Reaves State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 Steven W. Perry, Ron Malega, and Duren Banks Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 Todd Minton Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System Mark Motivans and Howard Snyder 4 June 2011 Content s Overview 7 Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities 9 The Tribal Law and Order Act, 2010 (TLOA; Pub. L. No. 111-211, 124 Stat. 2258, Section 251(b)) requires the Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS) to establish and implement a tribal data collection system and to support tribal participation in national records and information systems. This is the first BJS report on the status of tribal data collection activities as required by the act. It describes BJS’s activities between July 2010 and June 2011 to improve tribal law enforcement reporting to the FBI’s Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) and BJS’s direct collaboration with tribal criminal justice systems to collect data about tribal court systems. It summarizes data published by BJS on jails in Indian country, tribal law enforcement agencies, state prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction in Indian country, tribal youth in the federal justice system, and reporting to the UCR. It describes activities and funding opportunities to improve tribal crime data collection through programs such as the National Criminal History Improvement Program (NCHIP), the National Instant Criminal Background Check System (NICS), Byrne/JAG funding, and UCR training. Table 1.1. Tribes submitting crime data to the Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) Program and receiving Byrne/Justice Assistance Grant (JAG) awards, FY 2008-2010 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10 Table 1.2. Bureau of Justice Statistics planned program activities in response to the Tribal Law and Order Act . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 13 Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 15 Presents data on tribal law enforcement agencies from the 2008 Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies. This report defines the number and locations of tribal law enforcement agencies, service populations, and the number of sworn and nonsworn employees. It describes agency participation in traditional law enforcement (routine patrol, criminal investigation, and dispatching calls for service), public safety functions (emergency management, animal control, and fire services), specialized functions (search and rescue, tactical operations, and underwater recovery), and court-related activities (executing arrest warrants, enforcing protection orders, and serving process). The report details participation in multiagency task forces involving drug and human trafficking, gangs, violent crime, and antiterrorism. It presents data on community outreach efforts, such as school resource officers and community policing officers. Table 2.1. Tribally operated law enforcement agencies, by type of agency and number of full-time sworn personnel, 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 16 Table 2.2. The 25 largest tribally operated law enforcement agencies, by the number of full-time sworn personnel, 2008. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17 Table 2.3. Use of community policing and school resource officers by tribal police departments, 2000 and 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 18 Figure 2.1. Location of tribally operated law enforcement agencies, 2008 . 15 Figure 2.2. Selected law enforcement functions performed by tribal police departments, 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 18 Figure 2.3. Selected court-related functions performed by tribal police departments, 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 18 Figure 2.4. Selected special functions performed by tribal police departments, 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 19 Figure 2.5. Task force participation of tribal police departments, 2008 . . . 19 State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 21 Describes state prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction in Indian country under Public Law 83-280 (P.L. 280). This report examines the activities of prosecutors’ offices in states affected by P.L. 280 through either mandatory or optional jurisdiction. Six states have mandatory jurisdiction under P.L. 280 over crimes in Indian country: Alaska, California, Minnesota (except the Red Lake Reservation), Nebraska, Oregon (except the Warm Springs Reservation), and Wisconsin. The report also examines activities of prosecutors’ offices in the 10 states that have an option to assume jurisdiction over crimes in Indian country within their borders: Arizona, Florida, Idaho, Iowa, Montana, Nevada, North Dakota, South Dakota, Utah, and Washington. Using data from the 2007 National Census of State Court Prosecutors, this report describes the characteristics of state prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction for crimes committed in Indian country, including budgets, staffing, and caseload. It also examines the types of offenses committed in Indian country that were prosecuted in 2007. Table 3.1. Number of tribes participating in the Census of Tribal Justice Agencies in Indian Country, by P.L. 280 status, type of court systems, and state, 2002 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 22 Table 3.2. State prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction for crimes committed in Indian country, by P.L. 280 status, 2007 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 22 Table 3.3. Type of state prosecutors’ offices in Indian country, by P.L. 280 status, 2007. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 25 Table 3.4. Budget, staffing, and caseload of state prosecutors’ offices, by P.L. 280 status, 2007 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 25 Figure 3.1. State prosecutors’ offices reporting jurisdiction in Indian country under P.L. 280, 2007 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 23 Figure 3.2. State prosecutors’ offices reporting prosecution of specific crimes in Indian country, by P.L. 280 status, 2007 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 24 5Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 Contents (continued) Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 27 Presents selected findings from the bulletin Jails in Indian Country, 2009, released in February 2011 (NCJ232223). Data are based on an enumeration of 80 jails, confinement facilities, detention centers, and other facilities operated by tribal authorities or the Bureau of Indian Affairs (BIA) reported to the annual Survey of Jails in Indian Country. The report includes data on the number of adults and juveniles held, type of offense, number of persons confined on the last weekday of each month, average daily population, peak population, and admissions in June 2009. It also summarizes rated capacity, facility crowding, and jail staffing. Table 4.1. Inmates, rated capacity, and percent of capacity occupied in Indian country jails, 2004 and 2007-2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 28 Table 4.2. Jails in Indian country that held the majority of inmates in 2009 compared to 2008, by facility . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 28 Table 4.3. Number of Indian country jails, by percent of rated capacity occupied, June 2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 29 Table 4.4. Admissions and expected length of stay in Indian country jails during June, by facility size, June 2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 30 Table 4.5. Number of inmates confined in Indian country jails, by demographic characteristics, conviction status, and offense, midyear 2000, 2002, 2004, and 2007-2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 31 Table 4.6. Number of persons employed in Indian country jails, by job function, June 30, 2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 32 Figure 4.1. Inmates confined in Indian country jails, at midyear 2000-2004 and 2007-2009. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 27 Figure 4.2. Percent of rated capacity occupied, by type of inmate count, June 2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 29 Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 35 Presents findings on tribal youth processed through the federal criminal justice system between 1999 and 2008. Findings are from a recent study conducted by the Urban Institute under the Bureau of Justice Statistics’ Federal Justice Statistics Program (FJSP). This report describes the number of tribal youth in the federal system and examines how they are handled through the stages of the federal criminal case process, from arrest to confinement. It describes tribal youth demographic characteristics, offenses, and case outcomes, such as referrals for prosecution, dismissal rates, sentencing, and time served. Table 5.1. Reason for matters declined for prosecution with tribal youth suspects, 2005-2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 37 Table 5.2. Federally recognized tribes and enrolled members, 2005. . . . . 38 Table 5.3. Tribal and non-tribal youth admitted to the Federal Bureau of Prisons, by offense type, 1944-2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 41 Figure 5.1. Tribal youth referred to and prosecuted by U.S. attorneys, 2000-2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 35 Figure 5.2. Case-related reasons for declination, 2005-2008 . . . . . . . . . 37 Figure 5.3. Tribal youth admitted to the custody of federal prison authorities, and five federal judicial districts that committed the majority of tribal youth, 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 38 Figure 5.4. Maximum time in federal custody of juveniles adjudicated delinquent . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 39 Figure 5.5. Tribal youth in the Federal Bureau of Prisons, by status, at admission, 2000-2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40 Figure 5.6. Non-tribal youth admitted to the Federal Bureau of Prisons, by status, at admission, 2000-2009 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 40 Figure 5.7. Non-tribal youth admitted to the custody of federal prison authorities, and five federal judicial districts that committed the majority of tribal youth, 2008 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 42 Highlights Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities 9 � The Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS) consulted with tribal leaders through a variety of forums in 2010. � For the first time, the Bureau of Indian Affairs’ (BIA) submissions to the Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) were disaggregated by tribe and reported in Crime in the U.S., 2009. � The number of tribes eligible for Byrne/JAG funding increased from 5 to 22. � In 2008, 140 tribal law enforcement staff received UCR training. � BJS provided competitive funding opportunities for jurisdictions to improve criminal records. � BJS developed a multifaceted data collection system that both established new collections and enhanced current programs. 6 June 2011 Highlights (continued) Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 15 � Tribally operated law enforcement agencies employed nearly 4,600 full-time personnel, including about 3,000 sworn officers. � The largest tribal law enforcement agency, the Navajo Police Department, employed 393 full-time sworn personnel in Arizona, New Mexico, and Utah. � Eleven of the 25 largest tribal law enforcement agencies served jurisdictions covering more than 1,000 square miles. � Overall, tribal police departments cost about $257 per resident to operate during fiscal year 2008. � In addition to law enforcement functions, nearly all tribal police departments performed court-related functions, such as court security and serving process. � More than half of tribal police departments used community policing officers, and more than a third used school resource officers. � About 4 in 5 tribal police departments participated in one or more multiagency task forces. State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 21 � Ninety-three state court prosecutors’ offices in the 16 P.L. 280 states reported jurisdiction for felonies committed in Indian country under P.L. 280. � Seventy-three percent of offices with jurisdiction in Indian country reported prosecuting at least one felony case committed in Indian country. � Most offices in P.L. 280 states prosecuted at least one offense involving drugs (63%), domestic violence (60%), or aggravated assault (58%). � Eighteen offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states with jurisdiction for Indian country prosecuted at least one rape, and 12 offices prosecuted a homicide. � Of state prosecutors’ offices that reported jurisdiction for felony cases in Indian country under P.L. 280, 70% served judicial districts with populations of less than 100,000 residents. � Offices with jurisdiction for felony crimes committed in Indian country had an average operating budget of $5.2 million in 2007. Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 27 � The number of inmates confined in Indian country jails increased by 1.9% between midyear 2008 and 2009, reaching 2,176 inmates. � Between June 2008 and June 2009, the average daily jail population in Indian country increased by 12%, and the percentage of occupied bed space increased from 64.2% to 73.5%. � Eleven jails (14% of all facilities) held 51% of inmates confined at midyear 2009. � During June 2009, the number of inmates admitted to Indian country jails (11,357) was about 5 times the size of the average daily population (2,124). � The expected average length of stay increased by a half day from 5.1 days during June 2008 to 5.6 days during June 2009. � Indian country jail authorities reported no deaths in custody between July 1, 2008, and June 30, 2009, down from 4 reported deaths during the 12-month period ending June 30, 2008. � Attempted suicides by inmates declined from 78 in 2008 to 56 in 2009. � Indian country jails held fewer inmates for domestic violence at midyear 2009 (252), continuing the downward trend in the number held for this offense since 2007 (362). � The percentage of certified correctional officers working in Indian country jails increased steadily, from 63% at midyear 2007 to 79% at midyear 2009. Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 35 � In 2008, relatively few juveniles were referred to federal prosecutors (315 out of 178,570 suspects) or admitted to federal prison jurisdiction (156 out 71,663 offenders). � Tribal youth (70) comprised nearly half of juveniles (152) handled by the federal courts in 2008. � Federal judicial districts of Arizona, Montana, South Dakota, New Mexico, and North Dakota accounted for 94% of tribal youth investigated, 92% of those prosecuted, and 88% of those admitted to federal prison jurisdiction in 2008. � In 2008, about 72% of tribal youth were investigated for violent offenses, including sexual abuse (35%), assault (20%), and murder (17%). � About 40% of matters involving tribal youth were declined by federal prosecutors in 2008. � A greater share of cases involving tribal youth in U.S. district courts were terminated by conviction (91%) than by dismissal (9%). � From 1994 to 2008, the lowest number of tribal (72) and non-tribal youth (84) admitted to the jurisdiction of federal prison authorities occurred in 2008. � Admissions to federal prison jurisdiction among tribal youth declined 10% per year from 1999 to 2008, while non-tribal youth admissions declined 12% per year. � In 2008, tribal youth served an average of 26 months under federal jurisdiction, which was more than double the tribal justice system maximum sentence of 12 months. 7Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 Overview The Tribal Law and Order Act (TLOA), enacted July 29, 2010, requires the Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS) to (1) establish and implement a tribal data collection system and (2) support tribal participation in national records and information systems (P.L. 111-211, 124 Stat. 2258, § 251(b)). The act further requires the director of BJS to consult with Indian tribes to establish and implement this data collection system. The BJS director is required to report to Congress within one year of enactment, and annually thereafter, the data collected and analyzed in accordance with the act. This report describes activities in support of BJS’s tribal crime data collection system and summarizes findings published from that system between July 2010 and June 2011. Multifaceted data collection system Criminal jurisdiction in Indian country—federally recognized reservations, tribal communities, and identified trust lands—varies by the type of crime committed, whether the offender or victim was a tribal member, and the state in which the offense occurred. Due to the sovereign status of federally recognized tribes in the United States, crimes committed in Indian country are often subject to concurrent jurisdiction between multiple criminal justice agencies. Public Law 83-280 (P.L. 280) gave select states legal jurisdiction over tribal members to prosecute crimes that occur on the reservation under existing state laws. These mandatory P.L. 280 states include California, Minnesota (except the Red Lake Reservation), Nebraska, Oregon (except the Warm Springs Reservation), Wisconsin, and Alaska. P.L. 280 permitted other states to acquire jurisdiction over crimes committed in Indian country at their option. These optional P.L. 280 states assume jurisdiction, either in whole or in part, over Indian country within their boundaries, and include Arizona, Florida, Idaho, Iowa, Montana, Nevada, North Dakota, South Dakota, Utah, and Washington. In the remaining states, where P.L. 280 does not apply, federal and tribal governments maintain concurrent jurisdiction for major crimes committed in Indian country (as defined in the Major Crimes Act and subsequent amendments (18 U.S.C. § 1153)). Tribal governments have jurisdiction for all other crimes committed in Indian country that involve both an Indian offender and Indian victim. States retain jurisdiction for non-Indian crimes committed in Indian country—those in which neither the offender nor the victim is a tribal member. Due in part to these jurisdictional complexities, existing tribal data systems are often limited in scope and applicable only to certain jurisdictions or states. An effective tribal data collection system will include data from federal, state, local, and tribal agencies. The information maintained in this system should further be considered in light of the concurrent jurisdictional roles multiple agencies maintain in Indian country. Recent findings from the tribal data collection system 178 tribal law enforcement agencies operated in 2008 In September 2008, American Indian tribes operated 178 law enforcement agencies. These 178 agencies employed at least one full-time sworn officer with general arrest powers or the equivalent in part-time officers. The total includes 157 general purpose tribal police departments and 21 special jurisdiction agencies tasked with enforcing natural resources laws that pertain primarily to hunting and fishing on tribal lands. Tribes operated law enforcement agencies in 28 states and employed about 3,000 full-time sworn personnel. Eleven of the 25 largest tribal law enforcement agencies served jurisdictions of more than 1,000 square miles. (See Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008, page 15, for more information.) 83 tribal law enforcement agencies provided data through the Bureau of Indian Affairs (BIA) that met the FBI’s guidelines for publication Offenses known to tribal law enforcement agencies were reported by tribal agencies in the FBI’s Crime in the United States, 2009. Eighty-three tribal law enforcement agencies met FBI guidelines for data publication in the report.* Nearly 3,800 violent crimes and approximately 11,400 property crimes were known to *Crimes known to tribal law enforcement agencies are submitted to the UCR through the BIA. UCR data must be submitted by local law enforcement with a valid reporting number, and be complete for all 12 months of the year. Data submitted to the UCR must also meet FBI data quality guidelines for publication in Crime in the U.S. 8 June 2011 these selected tribal law enforcement agencies in 2009. (See the FBI’s Crime in the United States, 2009, http:// www2.fbi.gov/ucr/cius2009/data/ table_11.html, for more information.) 93 state prosecutors’ offices in P.L. 280 states reported jurisdiction for felonies committed in Indian country In 2007, 93 state court prosecutors’ offices reported jurisdiction under P.L. 280 for felonies committed in Indian country. Seventy-three percent of these offices reported prosecuting at least one felony case that arose from Indian country in 2007, including at least one offense that involved drugs (63%), domestic violence (60%), or aggravated assault (58%). Most state prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction under P.L. 280 served districts with 100,000 or fewer residents. (See State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007, page 21, for more information.) Jails in Indian country housed 2,176 inmates in 2009 The number of inmates confined in Indian country jails increased by 1.9% between midyear 2008 and midyear 2009, from 2,135 to 2,176 inmates. Over the 12 months ending June 2009, the average daily jail population in Indian country increased by 12%, and the percentage of occupied bed space increased from 64.2% to 73.5%. (See Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009, page 27, for more information.) Most tribal youth in the federal system were referred for violent offenses Between 1999 and 2008, 65% of tribal youth in criminal matters received by federal prosecutors were referred for a violent offense. Sexual abuse was the most common violent offense, followed by assault and murder. In 2008, federal prosecutors received 129 tribal youth suspects in matters opened out of 178,570 total matters investigated. Tribal youth admitted to the legal custody of federal prison authorities were mostly male (90%) and tended to be older teens; more than two-thirds were between the ages 16 and 17. (See Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System, page 35, for more information.) 9Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities, 2011 The Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS), in collaboration with other federal agencies and American Indian tribes, conducted several activities to develop the tribal data collection system as of June 2011. The data collection system establishes both new data collections and enhances current programs to carry out the requirements of the Tribal Law and Order Act (TLOA), 2010. BJS focused on improving tribal law enforcement reporting to the FBI’s Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) and developed direct data collection from tribal criminal justice systems, such as collecting information about the nature and operation of tribal court systems. Efforts also include activities and funding opportunities to improve tribal crime data collection through programs such as the National Criminal History Improvement Program (NCHIP), the National Instant Criminal Background Check System (NICS), Byrne/JAG funding, and UCR training. Activities to Support Tribal Crime Data Collection Systems, July 2010 through June 2011 Tribal consultations conducted in 2010 BJS consulted with tribal leaders through a variety of forums in 2010. BJS developed and distributed an initial plan that responded to the TLOA sections that directly referenced tribal crime data collection. This plan was presented to several stakeholder groups to invite feedback and input, including— � Interdepartmental Tribal Justice Safety and Wellness Consultation, Session 12 (December 2010, Palm Springs, CA) � Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) trainings for tribal law enforcement (2010) agencies � National Congress of American Indians, 2011 Executive Council Winter Meeting (March 2011, Washington, DC). For the first time, the Bureau of Indian Affairs’ (BIA) submissions to UCR were disaggregated by tribe and reported in the FBI’s Crime in the U.S., 2009 Working with the Office of Justice Services in the BIA, and the Office of Tribal Justice and the FBI in the Department of Justice (DOJ), BJS developed a process to support tribal access to, and input in, regional and national criminal justice databases, including the National Crime Information Center (NCIC) and the Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR). As a result of this process, data provided to the FBI from the BIA were able to be disaggregated by tribe. Offenses known to tribal law enforcement agencies were reported by tribal agencies in the FBI’s Crime in the United States, 2009. Eighty- three tribal law enforcement agencies met FBI guidelines for data to be published in the report. Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities, 2011 Duren Banks, Ph.D., and Steven W. Perry, BJS Statisticians Allina Lee, BJS Policy Analyst U.S. Department of Justice Office of Justice Programs Bureau of Justice Statistics June 2011, NCJ 234518 Highlights � The Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS) consulted with tribal leaders through a variety of forums in 2010. � For the first time, the Bureau of Indian Affairs’ (BIA) submissions to the Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) were disaggregated by tribe and reported in Crime in the U.S., 2009. � The number of tribes eligible for Byrne/JAG funding increased from 5 in 2008 to 22 in 2010. � In 2010, 140 tribal law enforcement staff received UCR training. � BJS provided competitive funding opportunities for jurisdictions to improve criminal records in fiscal year 2011. � BJS developed a multifaceted data collection system that both established new collections and enhanced current programs. 10 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 The number of tribes eligible for Byrne/ JAG funding increased from 5 in fiscal year 2008 to 22 in fiscal year 2010 Collaborative efforts between the departments of Justice and Interior have increased the number of tribes reporting monthly crime data to the UCR, thereby increasing the number of tribes eligible to receive Byrne/JAG awards. Byrne/JAG funds can be used to support a range of activities in seven broad program areas, including law enforcement; prosecution and courts; crime prevention and education; corrections; drug treatment and enforcement; program planning, evaluation, and technology improvement; and crime victim and witness programs. Most American Indian tribes had been ineligible to receive Byrne/JAG funds because of gaps in Indian country crime statistics and traditional methods for reporting data. Prior to 2009, BIA provided an aggregate number of crimes known to tribal law enforcement to the UCR. Since these data could not be disaggregated by tribe, tribal law enforcement agencies that did not submit information directly to the UCR were not eligible for Byrne/JAG awards. In FY 2008, 25 tribes submitted crime data directly to the FBI, with 5 of the tribes eligible to receive Byrne/JAG awards totaling $150,000. In FY 2010, the number of tribes that submitted crime data increased to 144 following collaborative efforts between agencies in the departments of Justice and Interior, with 22 tribes eligible for Byrne/JAG awards totaling $709,000 (table 1.1). More than 140 tribal law enforcement staff received UCR training Through Recovery Act funds, BJS developed and implemented the Tribal Crime Data project to further support the reporting of tribal crime to the UCR, and thereby establish eligibility for Byrne/ JAG funds. The project is also part of BJS’s larger effort to collect more reliable information on American Indians in the criminal justice system and crimes committed in Indian country. Through the Tribal Crime Data project, BJS conducted three training sessions in 2010, with more than 140 tribal members, on the use of the UCR systems. In 2011 the project provided training and technical assistance to tribes that did not meet FBI data quality guidelines or had not previously submitted complete crime data to BIA. Table 1.1 Tribes submitting crime data to the Uniform Crime Reporting Program (UCR) and receiving Justice Assistance Grant (JAG) awards, FY 2008–2010 Number of tribes— Fiscal Year Reporting to UCR Eligible for JAG award Eligible award amount 2008 25 5 $150,000 2009 106 20 559,000 2010 144 22 709,000 BJS, acting jointly with the Office of Justice Services, BIA (DOI), and the FBI (DOJ), will work with tribes and tribal law enforcement to establish and implement tribal data collection systems (P.L. 111-211 § 251(b)). 11Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities, 2011 Funding for improving criminal records To improve criminal records, BJS provided outreach to agencies in tribal jurisdictions through two competitive funding opportunities: � National Criminal History Improvement Program (NCHIP) solicitation, 2011 � National Instant Criminal Background Check System (NICS) Act Record Improvement Program (NARIP) solicitation, 2011. The TLOA made federally recognized tribes eligible for awards under BJS’s NCHIP. State and tribal entities apply for NCHIP funds to enhance the crime fighting and criminal justice capabilities of governments by improving the accuracy, utility, and interstate accessibility of criminal history records. Jurisdictions also apply for NCHIP funds to enhance records of protective orders that involve domestic violence and stalking, sex offender records, automated identification systems, and other state systems that support national records systems and their use for criminal history background checks. BJS released the FY 2011 NCHIP solicitation on January 13, 2011, and collaborated with other OJP components to disseminate information about the NCHIP funding announcement as broadly as possible. Tribal contacts were alerted via email to the funding opportunity, and the solicitation was posted to the BJS and DOJ Tribal Safety and Justice websites. Information about the NCHIP funding opportunity was also presented during several meetings and a consultation in the fall and winter of 2010. Additionally, BJS developed an addendum to the solicitation that identified priority funding areas and eligibility requirements for tribal applicants. The addendum outlined key tribal priority areas activities related to— � information technology systems to capture and transmit tribal issued domestic violence and stalking records to the FBI NCIC Protection Order File � automation and transmission of existing qualifying domestic violence and stalking records to the FBI NCIC Protection Order File. The NARIP implements the provisions of the NICS Improvement Amendments Act of 2007, enacted in the wake of the shooting tragedy at Virginia Tech and includes tribes as eligible entities. The NARIP funds provide assistance to eligible states and tribes to improve the completeness, automation, and transmittal of records needed by the NICS to identify persons prohibited from receiving or possessing a firearm. These records include prohibited mental health adjudications and commitments, felony convictions, felony indictments, fugitives from justice, drug arrests and convictions, domestic violence protection orders, and misdemeanor crimes of domestic violence. BJS will award FY 2011 NARIP funds to support efforts to improve the records used by NICS, by providing assistance to states and tribes to improve the completeness, automation, and transmittal of records to state and federal systems. BJS released the FY 2011 NARIP solicitation on March 15, 2011. The same process used to disseminate information about the NCHIP funding opportunity was followed to alert tribes to the NARIP solicitation. Subject to the availability of appropriated funds and any modifications or additional requirements that may be imposed by law, BJS plans to competitively award NCHIP and NARIP funds in FY 2011. Eligible applications will be evaluated and scored by peer reviewers, and funding will be made based on the selection criteria outlined in the solicitations. BJS is authorized to provide for improvements in the accuracy, quality, timeliness, immediate accessibility, and integration of state and tribal criminal history and related records (P.L. 111-211 § 251(b)(1)(H)). 12 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 BJS established new collections and enhanced current programs In addition to collaborating with other federal agencies to improve tribal law enforcement reporting to the UCR, BJS developed a plan to collect information about tribal criminal justice systems. This multipronged approach both established new collections and enhanced current programs that serve the purposes of the TLOA. Through its ongoing statistical projects, BJS provided information on (1) suspects and defendants processed in the federal criminal justice system, including federal prosecutions of crimes committed in Indian country, (2) the incidence of crimes known to law enforcement that occur on tribal reservations or were reported by Indian country law enforcement authorities, (3) the characteristics of tribal law enforcement agencies, and (4) the characteristics of jails in Indian country. BJS plans to begin collecting information about the nature and operation of tribal court systems in 2012 (table 1.2). Survey of Tribal Court Systems BJS developed the Survey of Tribal Court Systems to build on BJS’s previous Census of Tribal Justice Agencies (See Census of Tribal Justice Agencies in Indian Country, 2002, BJS Web, December 2005). The survey will gather administrative and operational information from tribal courts, prosecutors’ offices, and indigent defense providers operating in the estimated 190 federally recognized tribal justice systems in the U.S. Subject to the availability of appropriated funds and any modifications or additional requirements that may be imposed by law, BJS plans to award the Survey of Tribal Court Systems in FY 2011. BJS will work with the awardee and collaborating organizations to develop the data collection instrument and methodology. The instrument will include, at a minimum, measures of tribal court organization, court caseload, characteristics of prosecutors in tribal courts, and systems to provide indigent defense in tribal courts. Based on the results of the initial data collection, BJS will devise a strategy for conducting a regular data collection program among Indian country court systems. Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies The Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies provides data on staffing, functions, and expenditures. Data collected include the number of sworn and civilian personnel by state and type of agency, and functions performed by each agency. BJS analyzed and published findings from data collected in 2008, from the Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies program, including 178 tribal law enforcement agencies. Survey of Jails in Indian Country The Survey of Jails in Indian Country data describe jails, confinement facilities, detention centers, and other facilities operated by tribal authorities or BIA. The annual report from the Survey of Jails in Indian Country includes data on the number of adults and juveniles held, type of offense, number of persons confined on the last weekday of each month, average daily population, peak population, and admissions at midyear. It also summarizes rated capacity, facility crowding, and jail staffing. The most recent report that describes findings from the 2009 survey was released in February 2011. National Census of State Court Prosecutors In 2007 BJS conducted the National Census of State Prosecutors, which was the second complete enumeration of all chief prosecutors who tried felony cases in state courts of general jurisdiction. The census collected information about whether district The director of BJS will establish and implement a tribal data collection system (P.L. 111-211 § 251(b)). 13Tribal Crime Data Collection Activities, 2011 Table 1.2 Bureau of Justice Statistics Planned Program Activities in Response to the Tribal Law and Order Act Program Objective Timeline Collaboration with DOJ Components and BIA To increase the number of tribes eligible to receive Edward Byrne Memorial Justice Assistance Grant (JAG) Program funds, ensure tribal access to regional and national databases, and develop comprehensive tribal crime data systems. Ongoing. BJS Recovery Act Program To support tribes to more accurately and consistently report tribal crime data to the BIA and/or the FBI through technical assistance, training, and information sharing. Crimes known to some tribal law enforcement agencies published in Crime in the United States, 2009 and annually thereafter. Grants to Support Tribal Participation in Regional and National Databases To continue to include federally-recognized tribes as eligible entities for the National Instant Criminal Background Check System (NICS) Act Record Improvement Program and add federally- recognized tribes as eligible entities to the National Criminal History Improvement Program (NCHIP) grant awards. Tribes are eligible for awards as of FY 2009 (NICS) and FY 2011 (NCHIP). Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies To collect data from all state, local, and tribal law enforcement agencies on staffing, expenditures and functions. BJS will continue to implement strategies designed to accurately represent the work of tribal law enforcement agencies. Periodically since 1992. Latest report: 2004 census 2008 census report in 2011. Survey of Tribal Court Systems To gather administrative and operational information from tribal courts, prosecutors’ offices, and indigent defense providers. Award: August 2011. Design and Data Collection: 2011-2012. Analysis and Reporting: Early 2013. Survey of Jails in Indian Country The survey is an annual enumeration of jails, confinement facilities, detention centers, and other facilities operated by tribal authorities or the BIA. Data are collected intermittently via an addendum to the core survey on the physical conditions and operations of Indian country facilities. The addendum requests information on inmate medical services, mental health services, suicide prevention procedures, substance dependency programs, domestic violence counseling, sex offender treatment, education programs, and inmate work assignments. Annually since 1998. Latest report: 2009 survey 2010 survey report expected in 2011. Federal Justice Statistics Program To compile comprehensive information describing suspects and defendants processed in the federal criminal justice system. Ongoing since 1998. Annual data through 2009 available on the BJS website. BJS Native American Crime Information Website To provide users with easy-to-access and current information from existing and new data collection programs Design and populate website: 2010-2011. Public release: Late 2011. 14 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 2011 attorney offices have jurisdiction for prosecuting felony cases occurring in Indian country under P.L. 280, and what types of crimes the office prosecuted. The findings from this data collection are in State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country on page 21. Federal Justice Statistics Program The Federal Justice Statistics Program (FJSP) provides comprehensive and detailed information about the federal justice system’s processing of criminal cases. The FJSP provides annual data on workload, activities, and outcomes associated with federal criminal cases. Information is acquired on all aspects of processing in the federal justice system, including arrests, prosecution decisions, referrals to magistrates, court dispositions, sentencing outcomes, sentence length, and time served. The FJSP receives the source data from the U.S. Marshals Service, Drug Enforcement Administration, Executive Office of U.S. Attorneys, Administrative Office of the U.S. Courts, U.S. Sentencing Commission, and the Federal Bureau of Prisons. BJS is currently developing research projects that will examine American Indian defendants who are processed in the federal justice system. Findings from the first of these projects, describing characteristics of American Indian youth who are processed in the federal criminal justice system, are in the Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System on page 35. References Crime in the United States, 2009, U.S. Department of Justice, Federal Bureau of Investigation, September 2010. Jails in Indian Country, 2009, NCJ 232223, BJS Web, February 2011. State Prosecutors Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007, NCJ 234241, BJS Web, June 2011. Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008. NCJ 234217, BJS Web, June 2011. Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System, NCJ 234218, BJS Web, June 2011. Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 15 Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 Brian A. Reaves, Ph.D., BJS Statistician In September 2008, American Indian tribes operated 178 law enforcement agencies that employed at least one full-time sworn officer with general arrest powers or the equivalent in part-time officers. The total includes 157 general purpose tribal police departments and 21 special jurisdiction agencies tasked with enforcing natural resources laws that pertain primarily to hunting and fishing on tribal lands. Collectively, tribes operated law enforcement agencies in 28 states. Washington (24), Arizona (22), Oklahoma (19), and New Mexico (17) had the largest numbers of tribal law enforcement agencies (figure 2.1). These findings are based on the 2008 Bureau of Justice Statistics’ (BJS) Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies. In addition to tribally operated agencies, the Department of the Interior’s (DOI) Bureau of Indian Affairs (BIA) operated 42 agencies that provided law enforcement Highlights � Tribally operated law enforcement agencies employed nearly 4,600 full-time personnel, including about 3,000 sworn officers. � The largest tribal law enforcement agency, the Navajo Police Department, employed 393 full-time sworn personnel in Arizona, New Mexico, and Utah. � Eleven of the 25 largest tribal law enforcement agencies served jurisdictions covering more than 1,000 square miles. � Overall, tribal police departments cost about $257 per resident to operate during FY 2008. � In addition to law enforcement functions, nearly all tribal police departments performed court-related functions, such as court security and serving process. � More than half of tribal police departments used community policing officers, and more than a third used school resource officers. � About 4 in 5 tribal police departments participated in one or more multiagency task forces. U.S. Department of Justice Office of Justice Programs Bureau of Justice Statistics June 2011 NCJ 234217 No tribally operated LE agencies Under 5 agencies 5-9 agencies 10 or more agencies Figure 2.1 Location of tribally operated law enforcement agencies, 2008 Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics, Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies, 2008 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201116 services in Indian country. Nationwide, BIA employed 277 full-time sworn personnel in 2008. Along with direct oversight of its own programs, BIA also provided technical assistance and some oversight to tribally operated agencies. On the more than 300 federal Indian reservation areas in the U.S., police officers may be tribal, federal, state, county, or municipal employees. Some areas may be served by more than one type of officer. Commonly, tribal police department funding, administration, and employees are based on the Indian Self-Determination and Education Assistance Act of 1975, (Public Law 93-638 or P.L. 638). This law allowed tribes to assume responsibility for many programs previously administered by the federal government, including law enforcement. P.L. 638 agencies operate with tribal employees under contract and with financial assistance from the BIA. Tribally operated agencies can also function under a self-governance compact with the BIA. This arrangement provides block grant payments, allowing for more tribal control than the line item funding of P.L. 638 contracts. Full tribal control over law enforcement services exists where such services are entirely funded by the tribal government. Jurisdiction over offenses in Indian country may lie with federal, state, or tribal agencies, depending on the offense, offender, victim, and offense location. Most tribes have cross- deputization agreements, often with neighboring nontribal agencies. These agreements allow law enforcement personnel from state, local, and tribal entities to cross jurisdictions in criminal cases, and can be used to enhance law enforcement capabilities in areas where state and tribal lands are contiguous and intermingled. In some instances, the number of agreements is large. For example, the Cherokee Nation Marshal Service is cross-deputized with 50 municipal, county, state, and federal agencies. Tribal police departments employed 2.3 full-time officers per 1,000 residents In September 2008, the 178 operating tribal law enforcement agencies employed more than 4,500 full- time personnel, including about 3,000 sworn officers (table 2.1). The 157 general purpose tribal police departments employed 4,294 full-time personnel, including 2,835 sworn officers and 1,459 civilian personnel. These agencies employed an additional 129 part-time personnel, including 80 sworn officers (not shown in table). The 21 natural resources agencies employed 271 full-time personnel, including 164 sworn officers and 107 civilian employees. These natural resources agencies also employed 11 part-time personnel, including 7 sworn officers (not shown in table). General purpose tribal police departments had a combined service population of about 1.2 million residents.* This corresponds to about 2.3 full-time sworn officers per 1,000 residents, which was the national average for all local police departments as of 2007. (See Local Police Departments, 2007, BJS Web, December 2010.) Collectively, tribal police departments cost $257 per resident to operate for 2008 (not shown in table). In 2007 the national average for all local police departments was $260 per resident. *Based on the American Indian service population counts published in BIA’s American Indian Population and Labor Force Report, 2005. The service population is the total number of enrolled tribal members and members from other tribes who live on or near the reservation and are eligible to use the BIA- funded tribal services. The service population excludes any non-Indian residents served by a tribally operated law enforcement agency and other persons using roads, stores, casinos, and other public places on tribal land. Table 2.1 Tribally operated law enforcement agencies, by type of agency and number of full-time sworn personnel, 2008 Type of agency and number of full-time sworn personnel Number of agencies Number of full-time employees Total Sworn Civilian All agencies 178 4,565 2,999 1,566 General purpose police departments Total 157 4,294 2,835 1,459 50 or more 6 1,397 871 526 25-49 19 955 607 348 10-24 61 1,380 955 425 5-9 47 479 332 147 Under 5 24 83 70 13 Natural resources agencies Total 21 271 164 107 10-24 8 154 107 47 5-9 4 38 29 9 Under 5 9 79 28 51 Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 17 11 of the 25 largest tribal law enforcement agencies served jurisdictions of more than 1,000 square miles The 25 largest tribally operated agencies employed at least 25 full- time sworn personnel. The largest agency, the Navajo Police Department, employed 393 full-time officers to serve tribal lands in Arizona, New Mexico, and Utah (table 2.2). The next largest were the Seminole Police Department (Florida) with 144 officers, and the Salt River Police Department (Arizona) with 125 officers. The BIA service population for the 25 largest agencies ranged from less than 1,000 to about 200,000 residents. Although not all reservations are open to the public, many tribal law enforcement agencies deal with a significant number of daily visitors in addition to the resident population. The natural resources of tribal lands attract visitors, as do conference facilities and casinos. All of the 25 largest agencies had at least one casino operating within their jurisdictional area. The amount of land area served by a tribal law enforcement agency can be quite large. For example, the Navajo Police Department has jurisdiction over about 22,000 square miles, a larger land area than any county in the continental United States. Ten other agencies among the 25 largest had jurisdictional areas exceeding 1,000 square miles, a larger land area than any city in the continental United States. Table 2.2 The 25 largest tribally operated law enforcement agencies, by the number of full-time sworn personnel, 2008 Name and location of agency Number of full-time sworn personnel BIA service population, 2005 Full-time sworn personnel per 1,000 residents Reservation land area (square miles) Full-time sworn personnel per 25 square miles Navajo Police Department (AZ, NM, UT) 393 192,067 2.0 22,174 0.4 Seminole Police Department (FL) 144 3,165 45.5 141 25.5 Salt River Police Department (AZ) 125 7,313 17.1 81 38.6 Gila River Indian Community Police Department (AZ) 93 14,966 6.2 584 4.0 Tohono O’odham Police Department (AZ) 66 26,673 2.5 4,453 0.4 Choctaw Police Department (MS) 50 8,313 6.0 25 50.0 Oglala Sioux Tribe Department of Public Safety (SD) 49 43,146 1.1 3,159 0.4 Cherokee Indian Police Department (NC) 45 13,562 3.3 83 13.6 Muscogee (Creek) Nation Lighthorse Tribal Police (OK) 39 55,817 0.7 4,648 0.2 Miccosukee Police Department (FL) 36 589 61.1 128 7.0 Poarch Creek Tribal Police Department (AL) 33 1,567 21.1 0.4 -- Cherokee Nation Marshal Service (OK) 32 197,684 0.2 6,702 0.1 Choctaw Nation Tribal Police Department (OK) 32 99,371 0.3 10,613 0.1 Colville Tribal Police Department (WA) 32 5,052 6.3 2,117 0.4 Saginaw Chippewa Tribal Police Department (MI) 30 1,799 16.7 218 3.4 Tulalip Tribal Police Services (WA) 30 2,869 10.5 35 21.4 Warm Springs Tribal Police Department (OR) 30 4,079 7.4 1,011 0.7 White Mountain Apache Police Department (AZ) 30 12,213 2.5 2,628 0.3 Isleta Police Department (NM) 29 3,980 7.3 331 2.2 Yakama Nation Tribal Police Department (WA) 28 16,815 1.7 2,153 0.3 Pascua Yaqui Tribal Police Department (AZ) 27 14,787 1.8 2 -- Puyallup Tribal Police Department (WA) 27 24,016 1.1 29 23.3 Rosebud Sioux Tribal Police Department (SD) 27 22,293 1.2 1,388 0.5 Red Lake Tribal Police Department (MN) 26 10,338 2.5 880 0.7 Oneida Indian Nation Police (NY) 25 650 38.5 0.1 -- Note: Land area data are from the U.S. Census Bureau, and include reservation land only. --Reservation land area is less than 25 square miles. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201118 Tribal law enforcement agencies were responsible for a broad range of services and functions during 2008 Nearly all general purpose tribal police departments were responsible for traditional law enforcement functions, such as routine patrol (100%), responding to citizen requests for service (100%), special events and crowd control (98%), criminal investigation (96%), and traffic enforcement (96%) (figure 2.2). About 4 in 5 departments were responsible for parking enforcement (80%), and about 2 in 3 departments dispatched calls for service (66%). About 3 in 5 general purpose tribal police departments had full-time community policing officers A majority of tribal police departments used a community policing approach in their efforts to prevent crime and maintain partnerships with the communities they serve. About three-fifths (59%) of departments had full-time sworn personnel serving as community policing officers (table 2.3). As of September 2008, about 500 tribal police officers were designated as community policing officers. In 2000, 73% of tribal agencies reported using community policing officers, with about 700 designated as such. For more than a third (36%) of tribal police departments, community policing efforts extended into the schools, with 82 full-time sworn personnel assigned as school resource officers. Although the percentage of departments using school resource officers in 2008 was about the same as in 2000 (37%), the total number of officers was about half of 2000 levels. Nearly all tribal police departments performed a variety of court-related functions In addition to law enforcement duties, nearly all tribal police departments were responsible for a variety of court-related functions (figure 2.3). The most common functions were executing arrest warrants (95%), enforcing protection orders (92%), serving process (89%), apprehending fugitives (88%), and providing court security (75%). Table 2.3 Use of community policing and school resource officers by tribal police departments, 2000 and 2008 2000 2008 Community policing officers Percent of agencies using 73% 59% Number of officers 714 503 School resource officers Percent of agencies using 37% 36% Number of officers 162 82 0 20 40 60 80 100 Percent of agencies Dispatching calls Parking enforcement Accident investigation Crime investigation Tra�c law enforcement Special events/crowd control Responding to calls for service Routine patrol Type of function Figure 2.2 Selected law enforcement functions performed by tribal police departments, 2008 Figure 2.3 Selected court-related functions performed by tribal police departments, 2008 0 20 40 60 80 100 Percent of agencies Type of function Enforcing child support orders Serving eviction notices Inmate transport Court security Apprehension of fugitives Serving process Enforcing protection orders Executing arrest warrants Tribal Law Enforcement, 2008 19 Nearly half of tribal police departments were responsible for search and rescue operations Nearly 9 in 10 tribal police departments performed one or more special public safety functions, the most common being emergency management (65%) and animal control (64%) (figure 2.4). About a third (31%) provided emergency medical services. Nearly a fifth provided fire services (19%) and school crossing services (18%). More than half (58%) of tribal police departments performed at least one specialized function, such as search and rescue (43%), tactical operations (26%), or underwater recovery (10%). About 1 in 6 agencies operated at least one jail (17%), and about 1 in 10 agencies operated an overnight lockup facility separate from a jail (10%). (For more information, see Jails in Indian County, 2009, BJS Web, February 2011.) The 21 special jurisdiction agencies, whose primary focus was the enforcement of natural resources laws, performed a variety of functions as well. In addition to providing patrol and response services, a majority of these agencies performed the following functions: criminal investigation (82%), search and rescue (71%), apprehension of fugitives (59%), animal control (59%), traffic enforcement (59%), and dispatching calls for service (53%) (not shown in figure). About two-thirds of general purpose tribal police departments participated in a multiagency drug task force About 4 in 5 (78%) tribal police departments partnered with federal, state, and local agencies in multiagency task forces to combat crime problems in Indian country during 2008. These task forces allow participating agencies to share in pooled resources, information, and expertise across jurisdictional boundaries. Tribal police departments were most likely to participate in task forces formed to combat drug trafficking (66% of agencies) (figure 2.5). About 2 in 5 (41%) departments participated in multiagency gang task forces, and about a third (32%) participated in violent crime task forces. Smaller percentages of tribal police departments participated in anti- terrorism (17%) or human trafficking (9%) task forces. 0 20 40 60 80 Percent of agencies Jail operation School crossing services Fire services Tactical operations (SWAT) Emergency medical services Search and rescue Animal control Emergency management Type of function Figure 2.4 Selected special functions performed by tribal police departments, 2008 0 20 40 60 80 Percent of agencies Human tra�cking Anti- terrorism Violent crime GangsDrug tra�cking One or more types Type of function Figure 2.5 Task force participation of tribal police departments, 2008 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201120 Methodology The Bureau of Justice Statistics’ (BJS) Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies (CSLLEA) is conducted every 4 years to provide a complete enumeration of agencies and their employees. Employment data are reported for sworn and nonsworn personnel and, within these categories, by full-time or part- time status. Agencies also complete a checklist of functions they regularly perform, or for which they have primary responsibility. The CSLLEA provides national data on the number of state and local law enforcement agencies and employees for general purpose local police departments (including tribal agencies), sheriffs’ offices, the primary state law enforcement agencies, and special jurisdiction (e.g., natural resources) agencies. It also serves as the sampling frame for BJS surveys of law enforcement agencies. The 2008 CSLLEA form was mailed to approximately 20,000 agencies that were determined to potentially be operating on the reference date of September 30, 2008. This master list was created by compiling information from the following sources: � the 2004 CSLLEA � lists provided by Peace Officer Standards and Training offices, and other state agencies � an FBI list of agencies requesting new identifiers since the 2004 CSLLEA. Responding agencies were screened for eligibility and were excluded if any of the following conditions existed on the CSLLEA reference date of September 30, 2008: � The agency employed only part-time officers, and the total combined hours worked for these officers averaged less than 35 hours per week. � The agency contracted or outsourced to another agency for performance of all services. � The agency was closed, a duplicate listing, or otherwise an invalid entry on the master list. � The agency did not employ personnel with general arrest powers. � The agency did not operate with funds from a state, local, special district, or tribal government. � All sworn officers volunteered their time on an unpaid basis. Data on number and type of personnel were obtained from all eligible tribal agencies. For general purpose tribal police departments, the item response rates were as follows: community policing and school resource officers, 100%; agency functions, 99%; task force participation, 99%; and operating budget, 87%. References American Indians and Crime, NCJ 173386, BJS Web, February 1999. American Indian Population and Labor Force Report, 2005, U.S. Department of the Interior, Bureau of Indian Affairs, Office of Indian Services. Census of State and Local Law Enforcement Agencies, 2008, NCJ 233982, BJS Web, June 2011. Census of Tribal Justice Agencies in Indian Country, 2002, NCJ 205332, BJS Web, December 2005. Indian Country Law Enforcement Review, U.S. Department of Justice, December 1999. Jails in Indian Country, 2009, NCJ 232223, BJS Web, February 2011. Local Police Departments, 2007, NCJ 231174, BJS Web, December 2010. Policing on American Indian Reservations, U.S. Department of Justice, National Institute of Justice, NCJ 186185, September 2001. Tribal Law Enforcement, 2000, NCJ 197936, BJS Web, January 2003. State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 21 State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 Steven W. Perry, Ron Malega, Ph.D., and Duren Banks, Ph.D., BJS Statisticians In 2007, 93 state court prosecutors’ offices reported jurisdiction under Public Law 83-280 (P.L. 280) for felonies committed in Indian country. Seventy-three percent of these offices prosecuted at least one felony case that arose from Indian country in 2007, including at least one offense that involved drugs (63%), domestic violence (60%), or aggravated assault (58%). This report presents selected findings from the Bureau of Justice Statistics’s (BJS) 2007 National Census of State Prosecutors. Criminal jurisdiction in Indian country is divided among federal, state, and tribal governments. Jurisdiction in a specific incident depends on the nature of the offense, whether the offender or victim was a tribal member, and the state in which the crime occurred. Crimes committed in Indian country are often subject to concurrent jurisdiction between multiple criminal justice agencies. The Major Crimes Act (18 U.S.C. § 1153), as amended, grants concurrent federal jurisdiction for 16 major crimes committed by Native Americans occurring in Indian country. State jurisdiction for crimes committed in Indian country is primarily provided for under P.L. 280. Tribal courts maintain concurrent jurisdiction when federal or state jurisdiction is applied. State prosecutors’ offices generally do not have jurisdiction over crimes committed in Indian country due to the sovereign status of federally recognized tribes in the United States. However, state prosecutors’ offices in 16 states may exercise jurisdiction over crimes committed on tribal lands under P.L. 280. This law established state jurisdiction over offenses committed by or against American Indians in Indian country, including federally recognized reservations, tribal communities, and identified trust lands. P.L. 280 is mandatory for 6 states and optional for 10 states. Highlights � Ninety-three state court prosecutors’ offices in the 16 P.L. 280 states reported jurisdiction for felonies committed in Indian country under P.L. 280. � Seventy-three percent of offices with jurisdiction in Indian country reported prosecuting at least one felony case committed in Indian country. � Most offices in P.L. 280 states prosecuted at least one offense involving drugs (63%), domestic violence (60%), or aggravated assault (58%). � Eighteen offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states with jurisdiction for Indian country prosecuted at least one rape, and 12 offices prosecuted a homicide. � Of state prosecutors’ offices that reported jurisdiction for felony cases in Indian country under P.L. 280, 70% served judicial districts with populations of less than 100,000 residents. � Offices with jurisdiction for felony crimes committed in Indian country had an average operating budget of $5.2 million in 2007. Criminal jurisdic tion in I ndian countr y Tribal jurisdiction � Crimes committed by Native Americans in Indian country. Sentences are limited to a maximum 3-year sentence of incarceration per count and 9 years per case (124 U.S.C. 2258 § 234 (a) (b)). Federal jurisdiction � Pursuant to the Major Crimes Act of 1885. 18 U.S.C. § 1153 and subsequent amendments State jurisdiction � All crimes on tribal lands specified under Public Law 83-280. 18 U.S.C. § 1162 � Crimes committed on tribal lands in which neither the victim nor the offender is a tribal member. Note: Criminal jurisdiction in Indian country depends on several factors, including the identity of the defendant, victim, type of offense, and where the crime was committed. U.S. Department of Justice Office of Justice Programs Bureau of Justice Statistics June 2011, NCJ 234241 Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201122 According to the 2002 Census of Tribal Justice Agencies, 94 of the 123 responding tribes in mandatory P.L. 280 states relied on state courts. The 2002 Census was limited to American Indian tribes in the lower 48 states, so tribes in Alaska were excluded. The Census also found that 19 of 90 reporting tribes in optional P.L. 280 states relied on state courts (table 3.1). The federal government retains criminal jurisdiction for major crimes committed in Indian country in the remaining states where P.L. 280 does not apply. States retain jurisdiction for non-Indian crimes (those in which neither the offender nor the victim is a tribal member) committed in Indian country.* In 2007, 1,548 state court prosecutors’ offices were in states not affected by P.L. 280 and were excluded from this report. The 93 state prosecutors’ offices reporting jurisdiction under P.L. 280 in mandatory and optional states represent 14% of all state prosecutors’ offices in states affected by P.L. 280. Nearly all of these served districts that overlapped with or were adjacent to tribal lands (figure 3.1). Approximately a fifth of state prosecutors in mandatory P.L. 280 states reported jurisdiction for crimes committed in Indian country P.L. 280 gave select states legal jurisdiction over tribal members to prosecute crimes occurring on the reservation under existing state laws. These mandatory P.L. 280 states include California, Minnesota (except the Red Lake Reservation), Nebraska, Oregon (except the Warm Springs Reservation), Wisconsin, and Alaska (table 3.2). *Some tribes have been affected by states that have received a federal mandate to exercise jurisdiction outside of P.L. 280, e.g., through state-wide enactments, restoration acts, or land claims settlement acts (Tribal Court Clearinghouse, 2010, www.tribal-institute.org/ lists/jurisdiction.htm). Table 3.1 Number of tribes participating in the Census of Tribal Justice Agencies in Indian Country, by P.L. 280 status, type of court systems, and state, 2002 Number of tribes using— Participating in census Tribal justice systems Indigenous courts CFR courtsa Tribal courts Relying on state courtsb Mandatory states 123 39 8 9 37 94 California 88 7 2 7 7 74 Minnesota 12 12 3 0 12 4 Nebraska 4 3 0 2 3 2 Oregon 8 8 1 0 8 6 Wisconsin 11 9 2 0 7 8 Optional states 90 80 13 11 74 19 Arizona 17 16 3 0 16 0 Florida 1 0 0 0 0 1 Idaho 4 4 1 0 4 1 Iowa 1 0 0 0 0 1 Montana 6 6 1 0 5 0 Nevada 16 14 1 4 13 6 North Dakota 3 3 0 0 3 0 South Dakota 9 9 0 2 9 0 Utah 4 2 0 2 2 2 Washington 29 26 7 3 22 8 Note: The 2002 Census of Tribal Justice Agencies was limited to American Indian tribes in the lower 48 states. Source: Table reproduced from Census of Tribal Justice Agencies in Indian Country, 2002, NCJ 205332, BJS Web, December 2005. aCourt of Federal Regulations (CFR) operated by the Bureau of Indian Affairs (BIA). bTribes that rely on state court for jusidical services (e.g., felony courts, court-ordered treatment, and child support enforcement). Table 3.2 State prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction for crimes committed in Indian country, by P.L. 280 status and state, 2007 Number of offices— All prosecutors’ offices in P.L. 280 states* With jurisdiction for felony cases occurring in Indian country under P.L. 280 Prosecuting at least one felony case All P.L. 280 states 672 93 68 Mandatory states 294 56 47 Alaska 1 1 -- California 48 23 21 Minnesota 76 15 15 Nebraska 81 3 1 Oregon 31 7 4 Wisconsin 57 7 6 Optional states 378 37 21 Arizona 11 1 1 Florida 16 1 1 Idaho 34 6 4 Iowa 93 1 1 Montana 46 5 1 Nevada 15 2 0 North Dakota 43 2 1 South Dakota 58 1 1 Utah 26 3 2 Washington 36 15 9 Note: The 2007 Census of State Court Prosecutors included 2,330 offices, 66% (1,548) of which were located in states not affected by P.L. 280, and therefore were excluded from all analyses. --No information reported. *Excludes data missing for 110 offices. 23 M an da to ry P .L . 2 80 st at es Op tio na l P .L . 2 80 st at es In di an re se rv at io n (U .S . C en su s B ur ea u) Pr os ec ut or s’ o� ce s r ep or tin g ju ris di ct io n in In di an Co un try u nd er P .L . 2 80 Fi g u r e 3 .1 St at e p ro se cu to rs ’ o ffi ce s re p o rt in g ju ri sd ic ti o n in In d ia n c o u n tr y u n d er P .L . 2 80 , 2 00 7 N ot e: P ro se cu to rs ’ o ffi ce s i n no n- P.L . 2 80 st at es a re n ot sh ow n. So ur ce : B ur ea u of Ju st ic e St at ist ic s Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201124 In 2007, 19% of all state prosecutors’ offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states reported jurisdiction for felony cases occurring in Indian country. P.L. 280 permitted other states to acquire either complete or partial jurisdiction over crimes committed in Indian country at their option: Arizona, Florida, Idaho, Iowa, Montana, Nevada, North Dakota, South Dakota, Utah, and Washington. Ten percent of all prosecutors’ offices in optional P.L. 280 states reported jurisdiction for felony cases in Indian country in 2007. About three-quarters of offices with P.L. 280 jurisdiction prosecuted a felony case from Indian country in 2007 Sixty-eight of the 93 prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction in Indian country reported prosecuting at least one felony case committed in Indian country in 2007. Forty-seven offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states reported prosecuting at least one offense committed in Indian country, and 21 offices in optional P.L. 280 states reported prosecuting at least one offense committed in Indian country in 2007. Most offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states with jurisdiction for felony offenses in Indian country also reported prosecuting at least one drug-related crime (42 of 56 offices), domestic violence offense (40), aggravated assault (38), parole or probation violation (31), or a crime involving sexual assault or sexual abuse (30) (figure 3.2). Offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states with jurisdiction for Indian country also reported prosecuting serious felony offenses, including 18 offices that prosecuted at least one rape committed in Indian country and 12 offices that prosecuted a homicide. Prosecutors’ offices with jurisdiction in Indian country had an average of 16 assistant prosecutors on staff The 2007 National Census of State Prosecutors collected operational and administrative information from state prosecutors’ offices, including budgets, staffing, and caseload. Offices reporting jurisdiction for crimes committed under P.L. 280 were not asked to disaggregate office resources or operations by whether they were directed toward crimes committed in Indian country or elsewhere in the judicial district. The census asked respondents to provide or estimate the total number of felony cases closed in 2007. The survey did not ask respondents to provide information on the number of cases that arose from crimes committed in Indian country. This section describes the entire operations of the state prosecutors’ offices reporting jurisdiction under P.L. 280, not operations specific to crimes committed in Indian country. Homicide Rape Robbery Sexual assault/abuse Parole/probation violation Aggravated assault Domestic violence Drug-related All felony cases prosecuted in Indian Country, under P.L. 280 Optional P.L. 280 Mandatory P.L. 280 Number of o�ces 47 21 42 17 40 16 38 16 31 15 30 10 21 8 18 5 12 4 Figure 3.2 State prosecutors’ offices reporting prosecution of specific crimes in Indian country, by P.L. 280 status, 2007 State Prosecutors’ Offices with Jurisdiction in Indian Country, 2007 25 Most (71) state prosecutors’ offices that reported jurisdiction for felony cases occurring in Indian country under P.L. 280 served judicial districts with populations of less than 100,000 residents or were part-time offices. In mandatory P.L. 280 states, 7 of the 56 offices with jurisdiction in Indian country served districts with 250,000 or more residents (table 3.3). Offices with jurisdiction for felony crimes committed in Indian country had an average 2007 budget of $5.2 million, or an expenditure of about $31 per district resident. The median budget was $722,000. The office staff included an average of 16 assistant prosecutors, 3 victim advocates, 4 legal services staff, and 19 support staff (table 3.4). Offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states reported an average of 61 total staff, including 19 assistant prosecutors, 8 investigators, and 22 support staff. Offices in optional P.L. 280 states reported an average of 38 total staff, 11 assistant prosecutors, 1 investigator, and 14 support staff. Offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states, reported closing a similar number of felony cases in 2007 compared to optional state offices. State prosecutors’ offices in optional P.L. 280 states closed 1,784 felony cases in 2007, while offices in mandatory P.L. 280 states closed 1,699 felony cases. Table 3.3 Type of state prosecutors’ offices reporting jurisdiction in Indian country, by P.L. 280 status, 2007 Total P.L. 280 Status Population served Mandatory Optional All offices 93 56 37 Full-time offices serving a judicial district with— 1 million or more residents 4 2 2 250,000 to 999,999 5 5 0 100,000 to 249,999 13 8 5 99,999 or fewer 65 37 28 Part-time offices* 6 4 2 *Part-time offices are defined as those that reported a part-time chief prosecutor in 2007. Table 3.4 Budget, staffing, and caseload of state prosecutors’ offices, by P.L. 280 status, 2007 Total P.L. 280 status Mandatory Optional Mean Median Mean Median Mean Median Total resident population served 156,495 28,893 177,407 28,965 124,846 28,606 Total operating budget $5,173,831 $722,208 $6,560,838 $735,735 $3,074,577 $670,000 Budget per resident population served $31 $26 $35 $27 $25 $24 Total staffa 51 12 61 12 38 12 Chief prosecutor 1 1 1 1 1 1 Assistant prosecutors 16 3 19 4 11 3 Civil prosecutors 2 0 1 0 4 1 Supervisors 2 1 2 0 2 1 Managers 1 0 1 0 0 0 Victim advocates 3 1 3 1 2 1 Legal services 4 0 3 0 4 1 Investigators 5 0 8 0 1 0 Support staff 19 3 22 4 14 3 Felony cases closedb 1,733 300 1,699 300 1,784 275 Note: Statistics include imputed data for some offices. Data were missing for 3 offices that did not provide total operating budget, 1 office that did not provide staffing information, and 6 offices that did not provide the number of felony cases closed. See Methodology for more information. aAll staff statistics are presented as full-time equivalent staff, calculated as the number of full-time staff plus 50% of the number of half time staff. bIncludes all cases charged as a felony that had a judgment of conviction, acquittal, or dismissal, with or without prejudice, entered by the court. Cases closed include all felony cases closed by the prosecutors’ offices and include an unknown number of cases committed in Indian country. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201126 Methodology The 2007 National Census of State Court Prosecutors (NCSP-07) surveyed 2,330 chief prosecutors in the United States who handled felony cases in state courts of general jurisdiction. The census did not include municipal attorneys or county attorneys who primarily operate in courts of limited jurisdiction. This report describes characteristics of offices that reported jurisdiction for crimes committed in Indian country under P.L. 280 in 2007. Most (66%) state court prosecutors’ offices included in the 2007 census were in states not affected by P.L. 280 and are excluded from this report. The operational and administrative characteristics described in this report represent the functions of the entire office and are not restricted to those functions, staff, budget, or other resources specifically devoted to crimes committed in Indian country, unless otherwise noted. Data Imputations BJS relied on previously reported data and valid office characteristics to impute values for critical variables where missing. These critical variables, found in Table 3.4, include the total operating budget, total staff, full- or part-time status of chief prosecutor, number of assistant prosecutors, and number of felony cases closed. Critical variables that were missing in 2007 were imputed from the same office’s response to the 2001 Census of State Prosecutors wherever possible. For each jurisdiction with valid 2001 and 2007 data, an adjustment ratio was calculated as the ratio of the critical variable’s 2001 value to its 2007 value. All ratios greater than the 90th percentile were discarded for imputation purposes. For those offices missing 2007 data, a hot deck imputation procedure was employed to impute the adjustment ratio value from the office’s nearest neighbor in terms of state and population size. Where there were no suitable donors in the same state, a donor of similar population size was used. The 2001 data were then adjusted using the imputed adjustment ratio to create the imputed 2007 value for the critical variable where missing. This procedure was followed for 3 offices missing total operating budget, 1 office missing staffing information, and 6 offices missing the number of felony cases closed. Reference Census of Tribal Justice Agencies in Indian Country, 2002, NCJ 205332, BJS Web, `December 2005. Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 27 Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 Todd D. Minton, BJS Statistician At midyear 2009, a total of 2,176 inmates were confined in Indian country jails, a 1.9% increase from the 2,135 inmates confined at midyear 2008 (figure 4.1). This count was based on data from 80 facilities, including jails, confinement facilities, detention centers, and other correctional facilities, that were in operation in Indian country at midyear 2009. For 2008, the number of inmates was based on data for 82 facilities in operation at midyear 2008. The number of inmates held in Indian country jails between 2004 and 2009 increased by 25% from 1,745 inmates to 2,176. The number of jails in Indian country has increased between 2004 and 2009 The Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS) collected data from 68 correctional facilities in Indian country in 2004, from 79 in 2007, 82 in 2008, and 80 in 2009. The survey was not conducted in 2005 and 2006. Over the 5-year period, a number of facilities closed and new facilities became operational. Eleven facilities permanently closed between 2004 and 2009, and a total of 21 facilities were newly Highlights � The number of inmates confined in Indian country jails increased by 1.9% between midyear 2008 and 2009, reaching 2,176 inmates. � Between June 2008 and June 2009, the average daily jail population in Indian country increased by 12%, and the percentage of occupied bed space increased from 64.2% to 73.5%. � Eleven jails (14% of all facilities) held 51% of inmates confined at midyear 2009. � During June 2009, the number of inmates admitted to Indian country jails (11,357) was about 5 times the size of the average daily population (2,124). � The expected average length of stay increased by a half day from 5.1 days during June 2008 to 5.6 days during June 2009. � Indian country jail authorities reported no deaths in custody between July 1, 2008, and June 30, 2009, down from 4 reported deaths during the 12-month period ending June 30, 2008. � Attempted suicides by inmates declined from 78 in 2008 to 56 in 2009. � Indian country jails held fewer inmates for domestic violence at midyear 2009 (252), continuing the downward trend in the number held for this offense since 2007 (362). � The percentage of certified correctional officers working in Indian country jails increased steadily, from 63% at midyear 2007 to 79% at midyear 2009. U.S. Department of Justice Office of Justice Programs Bureau of Justice Statistics June 2011, NCJ 232223 0 400 800 1,200 1,600 2,000 2,400 Number of inmates 20092008200720042003200220012000 At midyear Figure 4.1 Inmates confined in Indian country jails, midyear 2000-2004 and 2007-2009 Note: The Survey of Jails in Indian Country was not conducted in 2005 and 2006. Midyear count is the number of inmates held on the last weekday in June. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201128 constructed. BJS estimated inmate population counts for 7 facilities in 2004 and 4 facilities in 2007 that did not respond to the surveys. All known operating facilities responded to the 2008 and 2009 surveys. (See Methodology for additional details on facility counts and participation in the surveys.) (See Methodology in Jails in Indian Country, 2009, NCJ 232223, BJS Web, February 2010, for additional details on facility counts and participation in the surveys.) On an average day in June, the percentage of occupied bed space increased from 64.2% to 73.5% At midyear 2009, the 80 jail facilities in Indian country were rated to hold 2,891 inmates, down from 2,963 in 82 facilities during the same period in 2008 (table 4.1). The average daily population (ADP) in June—the population measure used to calculate percent of capacity occupied—increased by nearly 12%, from 1,903 inmates (June 2008) to 2,124 (June 2009), while the capacity to hold inmates decreased by 2%. Consequently, the percentage of rated capacity occupied in Indian country jails increased from 64% to 73% during the period. On June 30, 2009, the 80 facilities held a total of 2,176 inmates and were operating at 75% of rated capacity, remaining relatively stable since 2007. From June 2004 to June 2009, the overall number of beds (or rated capacity) grew at a faster rate (34%) than the the inmate population (25%). Small number of jails held more than half of the inmate population Eleven jails held more than half (51%) of the total inmate population at midyear 2009 (table 4.2). Between midyear 2008 and midyear 2009, the population in these jails increased by 247 inmates (29%). In 2008, 9 of the 11 facilities held the majority of jail inmates in Indian country. Over the 365-day period, 6 jails that held the majority of inmates in Indian country in 2008 experienced large declines in their jail populations. The combined decrease in the size of the jail population in these facilities was 33% (90 inmates) from midyear 2008 to midyear 2009. Among the 11 facilities holding the majority of inmates in 2009, the Gila River Department of Rehabilitation and Supervision - Adult facility reported the largest decline (30 inmates or 17%) in the number of jail inmates. The jail population in this facility has decreased by 92 inmates (38%) from its peak of 241 inmates reported at midyear 2007. Table 4.1 Inmates, rated capacity, and percent of capacity occupied in Indian country jails, 2004 and 2007–2009 2004 2007 2008 2009 Number of inmates Midyeara 1,745 2,163 2,135 2,176 ADPb 1,622 2,046 1,903 2,124 Rated capacity 2,162 2,900 2,963 2,891 Percent of capacity occupiedc Midyear 80.7% 74.6% 72.1% 75.3% ADP 75.0 70.6 64.2 73.5 Number of operating facilities 68 79 82 80 aMidyear count is the number of inmates held on the last weekday in June. bAverage daily population (ADP) is the sum of the number of inmates held on each day in June, divided by 30. cPopulation as a percent of capacity occupied is calculated by dividing the population count of a facility by its rated capacity and multiplying by 100. Table 4.2 Jails in Indian country that held the majority of inmates in 2009 compared to 2008, by facility Custody population at midyear* Change in population Facility 2008 2009 Number Percent Total, 11 facilities 859 1,106 247 29% Tohono O’odham Adult Detention Center (AZ) 137 192 55 40% Gila River Department of Rehabilitation and Supervision - Adult (AZ) 179 149 -30 -17 San Carlos Department of Corrections and Rehabilitation - Adult and Juvenile Detention (AZ) 88 147 59 67 Truxton Canyon Adult Detention Center (AZ) 39 105 66 169 White Mountain Apache Detention Center (AZ) 101 95 -6 -6 Oglala Sioux Tribal Offenders Facility (SD) 52 95 43 83 Standing Rock Law Enforcement and Adult Detention Center (ND) 71 93 22 31 Nisqually Adult Corrections (WA) 59 73 14 24 Menominee Tribal Detention Facility (WI) 54 53 -1 -2 Navajo Department of Corrections - Shiprock Police Department and Adult Detention (NM) 46 52 6 13 Laguna Tribal Police and Detention Center (NM) 33 52 19 58 Note: Based on facilities that held the most inmates on June 30, 2009. *Midyear count is the number of inmates held on the last weekday in June. Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 29 Two facilities, the Truxton Canyon Adult Detention Center and the Laguna Tribal Police and Detention Center, were among the 11 facilities holding the majority of jail inmates in 2009. These 2 facilities were not among the 11 facilities holding the majority of inmates in 2008. (See Jails in Indian Country, 2008, BJS Web, December 2008.) The Truxton Canyon Adult Detention Center reported the largest increase in the inmate population (66 inmates or 169%) between midyear 2008 and midyear 2009. The Laguna Tribal Police and Detention Center increased by 58% (19 inmates) between 2008 and 2009. Based on the 80 facilities responding to the survey in both 2008 and 2009, the overall change in the inmate population (up 45 inmates) was relatively small. Thirty-three facilities, which were mostly the larger facilities, accounted for this increase (not shown in table). Change in the size of the jail population in Indian country was varied. More than half of the 80 jails experienced either a decline (40 jails) or no change (7 jails) in the size of their inmate population over the 12-month period ending midyear 2009. Overall, the 50% increase (415 inmates) in the jail population in 33 jails was offset by a 30% decline (370 inmates) in 40 jails. The use of jail space varied by facility size Indian country jails rated to hold 25 to 49 inmates were operating at 89% of their rated capacity on June 30, 2009, and at 79% on an average day in June. An average day in June was based on the ADP, or the sum of the numbers held on each day in June divided by 30. In contrast, the lowest percentage of capacity occupied during June 2009 was among the 11 small jails rated to hold fewer than 10 inmates. These facilities were operating at 21% of rated capacity at midyear and at 17% of capacity on an average day in June 2009 (figure 4.2). Compared to facilities in all other size categories, the large jails with a rated capacity of 50 or more inmates reported the only increase in occupied bed space between 2008 and 2009. The percentage of capacity occupied in these jails increased from 51% to 69% during the 12 months ending at midyear 2009, and from 49% to 73% on an average day in June 2008 and 2009. The amount of bed space occupied was also measured based on a facility’s most crowded day in June. Nearly half (38 facilities) of the 80 facilities in Indian country were operating above rated capacity on the most crowded day in June (table 4.3). Of those Table 4.3 Number of Indian country jails, by percent of rated capacity occupied, June 2009 Number of jails Percent of capacity occupieda Midyearb ADPc Peakd Less than 25% 17 20 7 25-49% 15 11 8 50-74% 19 21 15 75-100% 11 15 12 More than 100% 18 13 38 aPopulation as a percent of capacity occupied is calculated by dividing the population count of a facility by its rated capacity and multiplying by 100. bMidyear count is the number of inmates held on the last weekday in June. cAverage daily population (ADP) is the sum of the number of inmates held on each day in June, divided by 30. dPeak population is the population held on the day in June in which the custody population of a facility was the largest. 0 20 40 60 80 100 120 140 Peak 50 or more25 to 4910 to 24Fewer than 10 inmatesTotal Percent of capacity occupied ADP Midyear Figure 4.2 Rated capacity occupied, by type of inmate count, June 2009 Note: Rated capacity is the maximum number of beds or inmates assigned by a rating official. Midyear count is the number of inmates held on the last weekday in June. Average daily population (ADP) is the sum of the number of inmates held on each day in June divided by 30. Peak population is the population held on the day in June in which the custody population of a facility was the largest. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201130 facilities, 18 were operating above rated capacity on June 30, and 13 were operating above rated capacity on an average day during June 2009. High volumes of admissions of inmates were processed through Indian country jails Eighty Indian country jails admitted 11,357 persons during June 2009, up slightly from 11,149 admissions in 81 facilities during June 2008 (table 4.4). The number of admissions grew by 1.6% in the 79 facilities that reported data on admissions in both June 2009 (11,323) and June 2008 (11,147) (not shown in table). Admissions to facilities rated to hold between 25 to 49 inmates accounted for about 48% (5,503) of all admissions in June 2009, down from 59% of all admissions in June 2008. The largest Indian country jails accounted for less than 20% of all facilities and reported a total increase of nearly 75% in the number of jail admissions during the 12-month period. Admissions to the largest Indian country jails increased from 1,915 inmates to 3,342 from June 2008 to June 2009. The 15 jails rated to hold 50 or more inmates had the highest average number of admissions per month (233), compared to jails in all other size categories (not shown in table). Inmate deaths and attempted suicides in Indian country jails declined Indian country jail authorities reported no deaths in custody between July 1, 2008, and June 30, 2009, down from 4 reported deaths during the 12-month period ending June 30, 2008. Attempted suicides by inmates declined from 78 in 2008 to 56 in 2009. Expected length of stay was 5.6 days for Indian country jail inmates in June 2009 During June 2009, the expected average length of stay for inmates confined in Indian country jails was 5.6 days, up from 5.1 days during June 2008. Length of stay is the time held in custody from admission to release. The expected length of stay for inmates was the highest (9.1 days) Table 4.4 Admissions and expected length of stay in Indian country jails during June, by facility size, June 2009 Facility sizea Number of facilities ADPb Estimated June admissions Expected average length of stayc Total 80 2,124 11,357 5.6 days Fewer than 10 inmates 11 9 133 2.1 10 to 24 24 276 2,379 3.5 25 to 49 30 820 5,503 4.5 50 or more 15 1,018 3,342 9.1 Note: Detail may not sum to total due to rounding. aBased on the rated capacity, the maximum number of beds or inmates assigned by a rating official. bAverage daily population (ADP) is the sum of the number of inmates held on each day in June, divided by 30. cExpected length of stay was calculated by dividing the average daily population (ADP) by the number of June admissions, and multiplying by 30. See Methodology in Jails in Indian Country, 2009 for details on estimating expected length of stay. Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 31 Table 4.5 Number of inmates confined in Indian country jails, by demographic characteristic, conviction status, and offense, midyear 2002, 2004, and 2007–2009 Number of inmates held at midyeara Percent of inmates held at midyear Characteristic 2000 2002 2004 2007 2008 2009 2000 2002 2004 2007 2008 2009 Total 1,775 2,006 1,745 1,996 2,135 2,176 100% 100% 100% 100% 100% 100% Sex Male 1,421 1,618 1,346 1,582 1,678 1,754 80% 81% 77% 79% 79% 81% Female 354 388 398 414 457 422 20 19 23 21 21 19 Age group/sex Adults 1,498 1,699 1,546 1,743 1,882 1,919 84% 85% 89% 87% 88% 88% Male 1,214 1,399 1,222 1,415 1,498 1,571 68 70 70 71 70 72 Female 284 300 324 328 384 348 16 15 19 16 18 16 Juveniles 277 307 198 253 253 257 16 15 11 13 12 12 Male 207 219 124 167 180 183 12 11 7 8 8 8 Female 70 88 74 86 73 74 4 4 4 4 3 3 Conviction status Convicted 1,072 1,120 966 1,116 1,340 1,496 61% 57% 58% 59% 63% 69% Unconvicted 689 857 697 763 776 680 39 43 42 41 37 31 Type of offense Domestic violence ... 291 257 362 307 252 ...% 15% 18% 20% 15% 12% Assault ... ... 190 233 308 299 ... ... 13 13 15 15 Rape or sexual assault ... ... 34 45 42 42 ... ... 2 2 2 2 Other violence ... ... 79 108 177 168 ... ... 6 6 9 8 DWI/DUIb 274 226 195 137 184 229 17 11 14 8 9 11 Drug law violation 133 126 104 132 104 107 8 6 7 7 5 5 Other ... ... 569 804 954 955 ... ... 40 44 46 47 Offense not reported ... ... 317 175 59 124 / / / / / / Note: Detailed characteristics may not be equal to the total number of confined inmates because of incomplete data. See appendix tables 1-3 in Jails in Indian Country, 2009, NCJ 232223, BJS Web, February 2011, for a list of all facilities and inmate characteristics. aMidyear count is the number of inmates held on the last weekday in June. bIncludes driving while intoxicated and driving while under the influence of drugs or alcohol. ...Not collected. /Not reported. in facilities that were rated to hold 50 or more inmates, down from 10.3 days in June 2008. Inmates held in jails rated to hold less than 10 inmates experienced the shortest expected length of stay (2.1 days). Inmate characteristics remain relatively unchanged; the number held for domestic violence declined Inmate characteristics by sex, age, and offense have changed in absolute numbers since 2000 (table 4.5). However, the distribution within most categories remained stable between 2000 and 2008, with a change in the distribution of inmates by sex, conviction status, and offense type at midyear 2009. Adult males accounted for the largest portion of the inmate population in Indian country jails during the decade. The female jail population had small but steady increases from midyear 2000 to 2008, with a nearly 8% decrease in the size of this population between midyear 2008 and midyear 2009. Except for one juvenile female inmate, the decline was entirely among the adult female jail population. The percentage of convicted inmates increased from 57% in 2002 to 69% in 2009. Inmates confined for a violent offense made up about 37% of the jail population at midyear 2009, down from 41% at midyear 2008. Most (75%) of this decline was among the population held for domestic violence. Domestic violence (12%) and simple or aggravated assault (15%) accounted for the largest percentage of violent offenders held in 2009, followed by unspecified violent offenses (8%) and rape or sexual assault (2%). Since peaking at midyear 2007, the percentage of inmates held for domestic violence has steadily declined, from 20% in 2007 to 12% in 2009. The Gila River Department of Rehabilitation and Supervision - Adult accounted for a large portion of the decline in domestic violence offenders between 2007 and 2009. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201132 It reported a 38% decrease in the confined inmate population between midyear 2007 (241) and midyear 2009 (149), and a 74% decline in the number of inmates held for a domestic violence (from 180 inmates in 2007 to 46 in 2009). The number of certified correctional officers and in-service training steadily increased Seventy-nine Indian country jails employed 1,332 persons at midyear 2009 (table 4.6). About 69% (916) of all personnel were jail operations staff, including correctional officers and other staff who spent more than 50% of their time supervising inmates. The remaining 416 jail personnel included administrative employees, educational staff, technical or professional staff, clerical, maintenance, or food service staff, and other job functions. Overall, the ratio of inmates to jail operations employees was 2.4 inmates to 1 employee at midyear 2009, remaining relatively stable since 2008 (2.3 to 1) and 2004 (2.5 to 1). Seventy-six facilities reported that 710 (79%) correctional officers received basic detention officer certification, up from 69% in 2008 and 63% in 2007 (not shown). Seventy-four facilities reported that 750 (84%) correctional officers received 40 hours of in-service training, up from 74% in 2008 and 70% in 2007. Table 4.6 Persons employed in Indian country jails, by job function, midyear 2009 Job function Number Percent Totala 1,332 100% Administrativeb 136 10.2% Jail operations 916 68.8 Educational staff 29 2.2 Technical/professional 51 3.8 Clerical/maintenance/food service 173 13.0 Number of inmates per jail operations staff 2.4 aIncludes 27 other persons with unspecified functions not shown in table. bIncludes jail administrators, assistants, and other personnel who work in an administrative capacity more than 50% of the time. Selected Findings: Jails in Indian Country, 2009 33 Methodology The Annual Survey of Jails in Indian Country (SJIC) includes all known Indian country correctional facilities operated by tribal authorities or the Bureau of Indian Affairs (BIA), U.S. Department of the Interior. The survey was conducted in June 2009, and included the number of inmates and percent of capacity occupied based on the ADP, midyear population, and peak population in facilities in June 2009. (See table 10 in Jails in Indian Country, 2009, BJS Web, February 2011.) Through a cooperative agreement with the Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS), Westat, Inc. conducted the SJIC to describe all adult and juvenile jail facilities and detention centers in Indian country. For this report, Indian country includes reservations, pueblos, rancherias, and other appropriate areas (18 U.S.C.§ 1151). The reference date for the survey is June 30, 2009. Annually, BIA provides BJS a list of Indian country jail facilities, including detention centers, jails, and other correctional facilities operated by tribal authorities or BIA. BJS uses this list to update its existing roster of jails in Indian country. BJS obtains data from administrators of Indian country jails by mailed questionnaires and through follow-up phone calls and facsimiles. In 2004, BJS contacted administrators in 70 facilities to participate in the survey. BJS received responses from 61 facilities; 7 did not respond, and 2 facilities were non-operational. In 2007, the BJS roster consisted of 86 facilities. Seventy-nine of the facility administrators responded to the survey; 4 did not respond, and BJS found that 3 facilities were non- operational. In 2008, BJS’s roster of Indian country jails consisted of 85 facilities. BJS received responses from 82 facility administrators; there were no nonrespondents, and 3 facilities were non-operational. For 2009, the BJS roster consisted of 86 facilities. BJS received responses from 80 facility administrators; there were no nonrespondents, and 6 facilities were non-operational. For comparison over time, BJS estimated data on inmate populations for the 7 facilities in 2004 and 4 facilities in 2008 that did not respond to the surveys. Expected length of stay The stock-flow ratio method was used to measure the expected average length of stay for inmates held during June 2009 in the 80 Indian country jails that responded to stock and flow items in the survey: Stock—average daily population Flow—inmate admissions during June 2009 Stock-flow ratio in June 2009 (2,124/11,357=0.187) Expected length of stay in days (0.187 × 30)—is the average number of days held in custody from admission to release. Indian country is a statutory term that includes all lands within an Indian reservation, dependent Indian communities, and Indian trust allotments (18 U.S.C. § 1151). Courts interpret Section 1151 to include all lands held in trust for tribes or their members. (See United States v. Roberts, 185 F.3d 1125 (10th Cir. 1999).) Tribal authority to imprison American Indian offenders is limited to one year per offense by statute (25 U.S.C. § 1302), a $5,000 fine, or both. Tribal law enforcement agencies act as first responders to both felony and misdemeanor crimes. For most of Indian country, the federal government provides felony law enforcement concerning crimes by or against Indians. Certain areas of Indian country are under Public Law 83-280, as amended. P.L. 280 conferred jurisdiction on certain states over Indian country and suspended enforcement of the Major Crimes Act (18 U.S.C. § 1153) and the General Crimes Act (18 U.S.C. § 1152) in those areas. Indian tribes retain concurrent jurisdiction to enforce laws in Indian country where P.L. 280 applies. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201134 Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 35 Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System Mark Motivans, Ph.D., and Howard Snyder, Ph.D., BJS Statisticians The federal criminal justice response to tribal youth varies by the state in which the offense occurred, the nature of the offense, the availability of community- and confinement-based services, and discretionary decisions made by tribal, state, and federal justice agencies. Cases involving tribal youth in the federal system may result in 1) a delinquency adjudication and court-ordered supervision and out-of-home placement, or 2) the youth being transferred to adult status and prosecuted and sentenced as an adult. This summary describes the federal response to tribal youth during the case-processing stages from investigation to corrections. In this report, a federal juvenile delinquent is a person who has committed an offense while under age 18, and the federal prosecutor has certified a federal basis for jurisdiction. Juvenile and youth are used interchangeably in this report. The number of tribal youth in matters concluded by federal prosecutors and the total number of tribal youth prosecuted decreased from 2003 to 2008 (figure 5.1). Tribal youth in matters concluded by federal prosecutors dropped to 115 in 2008, down from 230 in 2003. Highlights � In 2008, relatively few juveniles were referred to federal prosecutors (315 out of 178,570 suspects) or admitted to federal prison jurisdiction (156 out 71,663 offenders). � Tribal youth (70) comprised nearly half of juveniles (152) handled by the federal courts in 2008. � Federal judicial districts of Arizona, Montana, South Dakota, New Mexico, and North Dakota accounted for 94% of tribal youth investigated, 92% of those prosecuted, and 88% of those admitted to federal prison jurisdiction in 2008. � In 2008, about 72% of tribal youth were investigated for violent offenses, including sexual abuse (35%), assault (20%), and murder (17%). � About 40% of matters involving tribal youth were declined by federal prosecutors in 2008. � A greater share of cases involving tribal youth in U.S. district courts were terminated by conviction (91%) than by dismissal (9%). � From 1994 to 2008, the lowest number of tribal (72) and non-tribal youth (84) admitted to the jurisdiction of federal prison authorities occurred in 2008. � Admissions to federal prison jurisdiction among tribal youth declined 10% per year from 1999 to 2008, while non-tribal youth admissions declined 12% per year. � In 2008, tribal youth served an average of 26 months under federal jurisdiction, which was more than double the tribal justice system maximum sentence of 12 months. U.S. Department of Justice Office of Justice Programs Bureau of Justice Statistics June 2011, NCJ 234218 Findings presented in this report are mostly from a recent study conducted by The Urban Institute under a cooperative agreement with the Bureau of Justice Statistics (BJS). The study was also sponsored by the Office of Juvenile Justice and Delinquency Prevention (OJJDP). See page 43 for more information. Figure 5.1 Tribal youth in matters concluded and in matters prosecuted by U.S. attorneys, 2000–2008 Number of tribal youth Fiscal year 0 50 100 150 200 250 Suspects in matters prosecuted Suspects in matters concluded 200820072006200520042003200220012000 Source: Urban Institute analysis. See Methodology for more information. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201136 Tracking tribal youth through the stages of the federal criminal case process The federal criminal justice system is not currently well- equipped to monitor how tribal juvenile offenders are processed across stages. There is a lack of unified, system-wide data standards in reporting how youth— especially tribal youth—are handled in the federal system. Juveniles or offenses committed in Indian country are not systematically tracked across the federal justice agencies. Researchers have to devise analytic methods to identify tribal youth using administrative data from each criminal justice stage (arrest, sentencing, and corrections). How is federal jurisdic tion over tribal juvenile delinquents determined? The determination of jurisdiction over offenses occurring in Indian country is first subject to whether state courts have jurisdiction based on Public Law 280 (P.L. 280).1 If a state has P. L. 280 status, jurisdiction over offenses occurring in Indian country lies with the state or tribal courts, not the federal courts. The determination of whether federal jurisdiction applies next depends on the offender and victim in the crime: � If the offender is a juvenile tribal member and the victim is also a tribal member, and the offense is 1 of 15 crimes covered by the Major Crimes Act then jurisdiction is with both the tribal and federal courts.2 � If the offender is a juvenile tribal member and the victim is a non-tribal member, and the crime is covered by the Major Crimes Act or federal enclave status, then federal and tribal courts have shared jurisdiction. The Assimilative Crimes Act permits state law to be applied in federal court where the Major Crimes Act does not apply but federal interest exists. � If the crime involves a non-tribal offender and a tribal member victim, then federal courts have exclusive jurisdiction. Once federal jurisdiction has been established, the Federal Juvenile Delinquency Act (FJDA) provides the procedures to bring the tribal youth to federal court. A federal juvenile delinquent is defined as a person who has committed an offense while less than 18 years old, but has not reached age 21 at sentencing. Juvenile and youth are used interchangeably in this report. How are juveniles handled in the federal justice system? Most juveniles, or persons under age 18, in the United States are handled in state or local courts, which have a separate juvenile justice system, rather than in the federal courts. Federal law permits handling of juveniles in the federal system only in limited circumstances. Apart from those committing crimes in Indian country or on military bases, juveniles that commit offenses as members of drug trafficking gangs, violent criminal gangs, or other federal offenses may be subject to federal jurisdiction. In these cases, the U.S. attorney for each district must certify to the district court that (1) the juvenile court or court of a state does not have jurisdiction or refuses to assume jurisdiction; 2) the state does not have available programs or services adequate for the needs of juveniles; or 3) the offense charged is a felony crime of violence or specified drug offenses, and there is substantial federal interest in the case. I n what circumstances are tribal and non- tribal juveniles transferred to adult status (for prosecution and sentencing as an adult rather than a juvenile delinquent)? Once federal jurisdiction has been determined and certification of delinquency established, a transfer hearing establishes the status of juveniles as to whether they will be transferred for prosecution as an adult. Felony crimes of violence or drug or firearm offenses trigger eligibility for adult transfer with certain age restrictions. Age thirteen is the minimum age for transfer to adult status for murder and assault, and for robbery, bank robbery, or aggravated sexual abuse with a firearm. An exception is crimes committed in Indian country where the tribe has opted not to permit prosecution of juveniles age 13 as adults. Age fifteen is the minimum age for transfer to adult status for committing any crime of violence (including physical force against a person or property). A juvenile can be housed in a Federal Bureau of Prisons (BOP) institution at age 18 if sentenced as an adult. BOP does not operate its own facilities for juveniles; rather, they contract with private entities and state and local governments for both secure and non-secure (community- based) juvenile facilities to house tribal and non-tribal youth under their jurisdiction. 1Congress passed Public Law 280 in 1953, which relinquishes the federal government of criminal and civil jurisdiction in certain states and places jurisdiction with those states. 2The Major Crimes Act provides federal jurisdiction over certain offenses committed by tribal members. (See Title 18 U.S.C. §§ 1152, 1153.) Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 37 Table 5.1 Reason for matters declined for prosecution with tribal youth suspects, 2005–2008 Reasons for declinations Fiscal year Matters concluded Number of declinations Case- relateda Suspect- relatedb No crime Referred to other authoritiesc OtherTotal 2005 172 69 100% 58% 10% 9% 13% 10% 2006 164 80 100% 61 10 10 13 6 2007 143 68 100% 47 15 10 18 10 2008 115 46 100% 50 7 15 20 8 aIncludes weak evidence, stale case, witness problems, or jurisdiction or venue problems. bIncludes age of offender and offender ‘s criminal history and drug/alcohol use. cIncludes pretrial alternative resolutions, such as pretrial diversion. Source: Urban Institute analysis of Executive Office for U.S. Attorneys, National LIONS data base, fiscal years 2005–2008. Investigation and Prosecution Tribal police are often the first to respond to a crime in Indian country. Offenses committed by tribal youth may be investigated by a combination of tribal police and federal law enforcement agencies. The federal Bureau of Investigation (FBI) and the Bureau of Indian Affairs (BIA) are the primary federal law enforcement agencies investigating tribal youth matters. Tribal youth commonly enter the federal justice system with an arrest for a warrant issued on either a complaint or juvenile information (written accusation made by the prosecutor). For serious offenses that may indicate a federal crime, the U.S. attorney’s office in the district is notified as is the juvenile’s parent/guardian. The juvenile must be taken before a U.S. magistrate as soon as possible, where charges are read and the juvenile is informed of rights. Federal prosecutors next determine if the matter should be adjudicated in federal courts, disposed by U.S. magistrate, or declined for prosecution. In 2008, 4 in 10 matters involving a tribal youth were declined by federal prosecutors During 2008, 40% of tribal youth in matters concluded were declined for further prosecution, which was lower than the 46% declination rate for non-tribal youth in 2008. However, the average declination rate for tribal youth (45%) was higher than for non- tribal youth (37%) from 2004 to 2008. The most common reason for declination of tribal youth matters in 2008 was case related (50%) (table 5.1). Case-related reasons included weak evidence, stale case, witness problems, and jurisdiction or venue problems (figure 5.2). Some declined matters involved tribal youth that were subsequently referred to other authorities for prosecution, such as to the tribe or the state where the tribe is located. The share of declinations for tribal youth that were referred to other authorities or received an alternative resolution increased from 13% of all declinations in 2005 to 20% in 2008. Among non-tribal youth, the most common reason for declination (71%) was that the suspect was a juvenile (not shown in table). Most tribal youth in matters referred to U.S. attorneys were prosecuted by federal prosecutors In 2008, 59% of tribal youth who were referred to federal prosecutors were prosecuted, which was higher than the 54% prosecution rate for non-tribal youth in 2008 (including matters disposed by U.S. magistrates). From 2004 to 2008, the averageprosecution rate for tribal youth (55%) was comparable to that of non-tribal youth (53%). Various factors go into the decision to prosecute a matter, including seriousness of the crime, strength of the evidence, youth’s criminal history and drug/alcohol use, tribal capacity to prosecute, and tribal preference. Tribes having concurrent jurisdiction with federal jurisdiction may have limitations on available secure placement options and treatment resources. The potential penalty that could be received if a matter was handled in tribal or state venues may also be considered.3 3The Indian Civil Rights Act (Title 25 U.S.C. § 1302(7)), for example, limited tribes in sentencing persons convicted of serious crimes to a maximum of 1 year in jail and a $5,000 fine. Recently, the Tribal Law and Order Act extended the maximum sentence that a tribe can impose to three years. Figure 5.2 Case-related reasons for matters declined for prosecution with tribal youth suspects, 2005–2008 Jurisdiction or venue problems Stale case Witness problems Weak evidence Percent of cases 77% 13% 8% 2% Source: Urban Institute analysis of Executive Office for U.S. Attorneys, National LIONS data base, fiscal years 2005–2008. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201138 Nearly 9 of 10 tribal youth admitted to Federal Bureau of Prisons jurisdiction from 2006 to 2008 came from five federal judicial districts From 2006 to 2008, 85% of tribal youth admitted to the jurisdiction of the Federal Bureau of Prisons (BOP) were from these five federal judicial districts: Arizona, Montana, New Mexico, North Dakota, and South Dakota (figure 5.3). The most recent tribal population data from the Bureau of Indian Affairs (2005) showed that these five districts contained 12% of the 590 federally recognized tribal entities and 35% of the more than 1.9 million total tribal enrollment population (table 5.2). Thirty-four percent of the enrolled tribal population under age 16 resided on or near reservations in these five federal judicial districts. Table 5.2 Federally recognized tribes and enrolled members, 2005 Tribal entities Tribal enrollment Tribal population under age 16 Federal judicial district Number Percent Number Percent District rank Number Percent of total enrollment District rank Total 590 100% 1,978,099 100% ~ 503,958 100% ~ Arizona 22 3.7% 269,778 13.6% 2 70,854 14.1% 2 New Mexico 25 4.2 174,199 8.8 3 43,234 8.6 4 South Dakota 8 1.4 115,513 5.8 5 27,534 5.5 6 Montana 8 1.4 66,962 3.4 6 14,957 3 9 North Dakota 6 1 58,220 2.9 8 13,851 2.7 10 All other districts 521 88.3 1,293,427 65.4 ~ 333,528 66.2 ~ ~Not available. Source: U.S. Department of the Interior, Bureau of Indian Affairs. American Indian Population and Labor Force Report, 2005, available at: http://www.bia.gov/ WhatWeDo/Knowledge/Reports/index.htm, calendar year 2005. 45–87 16–4416–44 1–151–15 0 District of Arizona (14%) District of New Mexico (12%) District of Montana (28%) District of North Dakota (4%) District of South Dakota (27%) Number of tribal youth admitted Figure 5.3 Tribal youth admitted to the jurisdiction of the Federal Bureau of Prisons, and five federal judicial districts that committed the majority of tribal youth, 2006–2008 Source: Bureau of Justice Statistics analysis of data from the Federal Bureau of Prisons, SENTRY database, fiscal years 2006–2008. Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 39 Adjudication and Sentencing Federal statutes provide for a youth’s release pending trial to a parent/ guardian, unless it is determined that detention is necessary to ensure a timely appearance or to ensure safety of juveniles or others (Title 18 U.S.C. § 5034). The federal pretrial services agency oversees supervision of the youth on pretrial release. For juveniles detained, a foster home or community-based facility near the youth’s home community is sought. Pretrial juveniles are not to be detained in facilities permitting regular contact with adult offenders nor with other juveniles who have been adjudicated. In 2008, 91% of cases terminated in U.S. district court involving tribal youth resulted in conviction Most (91%) tribal youth cases terminated ended in conviction in 2008. Most of the convictions were the result of a guilty plea (88%) than a determination of guilt at trial (3%). In comparison, 95% of non-tribal youth were convicted in 2008, with 91% resulting from guilty pleas and 5% following trial. From 2004 to 2008, the average conviction rate for tribal youth (92%) was higher than for non- tribal youth (87%). In juvenile adjudication proceedings, the judge has the discretion to impose an out-of-home placement, probation and conditions of probation, or restitution. The youth may also be transferred to adult status and prosecuted and sentenced as an adult. An adjudicated juvenile can receive up to 3 years of probation. The duration of a sentence for youth adjudicated delinquent to the jurisdiction of federal prison authorities depends on the age of the juvenile at disposition (see text box below). Juveniles under the age of 18 are not allowed to be placed in an institution in which the youth has regular contact with incarcerated adults. A juvenile can be housed in a Federal Bureau of Prisons (BOP) institution at the age of 21 if sentenced as a juvenile. The maximum time under federal jurisdiction of juveniles adjudicated delinquent depends on the age at disposition � If a juvenile was under 18 years of age at time of disposition, detention may not extend beyond the juvenile reaching age 21 (figure 5.4). � If a juvenile was between the ages of 18 and 21 at time of disposition, the maximum federal jurisdiction is 5 years. � Juveniles adjudicated delinquent and under the age of 21 are not to be detained in facilities permitting regular contact with adult convicts. At age 21, however, an adjudicated delinquent can be placed in an adult facility. � The term that an adjudicated delinquent receives may not exceed the maximum period of imprisonment authorized had the juvenile been an adult. Federal sentencing guidelines do not apply to adjudications of delinquency. 11 or younger 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 Maximum age in federal jurisdiction is 21 if age at disposition is under 18 years Age at disposition Maximum age of federal jurisdiction For disposition between ages 18 and 21, the maximum length of federal jurisdiction is 5 years Age of delinquent at disposition Figure 5.4 Maximum time under federal jurisdiction of juveniles adjudicated delinquent, by age at disposition Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201140 Corrections The number of tribal youth admitted to BOP jurisdiction increased from 107 in 1994 to a peak of 252 in 2000— a 136% increase due exclusively to the growth in tribal youth handled as adjudicated delinquents (figure 5.5). The number of tribal youth admitted to the BOP subsequently decreased from 252 in 2000 to 72 in 2008. In 2008, the number of tribal (72) and non-tribal youth (84) admitted to the jurisdiction of federal prison authorities was the lowest in the period from 1994 to 2008. From 1999 to 2008, the number of tribal youth admissions declined an annual average of 10%, and non-tribal admissions declined at an annual average of 12%. Tribal youth peaked at 252 admissions in 2000, and non- tribal youth peaked at 272 admissions in 1999 (figure 5.6). Most (88%) of the decline in tribal youth from 1999 to 2008 was due to a decrease in youth who had been adjudicated delinquent. Twelve percent of the decline was due to a decrease in tribal youth who had been transferred to adult status. In comparison, most of the decline for non-tribal youth admitted to the BOP over this period was comprised of juveniles who had been transferred to adult status. In 2008, 72% of tribal youth were admitted to BOP jurisdiction for a violent offense, including sexual abuse (29%), assault (25%), and murder (15%) (table 5.3). Tribal youth admitted for property offenses (mostly burglary) peaked in 2000 (66) and began to decline in 2001, dropping to 14 admissions in 2008. By 2008, tribal youth admitted to BOP jurisdiction for both property and violent offenses had declined to the lowest levels since 1999. Among non-tribal youth admitted to BOP jurisdiction, violent and drug offenses comprised the majority of offense types (not shown in table). Most tribal youth admitted to BOP jurisdiction from 1999 to 2008 had been adjudicated delinquent (83%), while most non-tribal youth had been prosecuted as adults (65%). 0 50 100 150 200 250 300 Tribal-transferred as adult Tribal-adjudicated delinquent 200820072006200520042003200220012000199919981997199619951994 Number of tribal youth Fiscal year Figure 5.5 Tribal youth admitted to the jurisdiction of the Federal Bureau of Prisons, by status at admission, 1994–2008 Note: Data for fiscal years 1999–2008 based on Urban Institute analysis of Federal Bureau of Prisons, SENTRY database. Data for fiscal years 1994–1998 based on BJS analysis of SENTRY data. 0 50 100 150 200 250 300 Non-tribal-transferred as adult Non-tribal-adjudicated delinquent 200820072006200520042003200220012000199919981997199619951994 Number of non-tribal youth Fiscal year Figure 5.6 Non-tribal youth admitted to the jurisdiction of the Federal Bureau of Prisons, by status at admission, 1994–2008 Note: Data for fiscal years 1999–2008 based on Urban Institute analysis of Federal Bureau of Prisons, SENTRY database. Data for fiscal years 1994–1998 based on BJS analysis of SENTRY data. Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 41 At yearend 2003, 298 tribal youth were in BOP facilities, including both juvenile contract and adult facilities In 2003, 74% of tribal youth were housed under BOP jurisdiction in Minnesota, Arizona, Utah, the Western District of Texas, and Colorado. BOP facilities (including contract facilities) were not located in the states that contained large tribal populations and had committed a large number of Indian country juveniles (South Dakota, North Dakota, Montana, and New Mexico). For example, tribal youth whose legal residence was South Dakota comprised over half of the juveniles in BOP facilities in Minnesota. Among tribal youth under BOP jurisdiction in 2003, most were committed for a violent felony offense, including homicide, manslaughter, serious sexual assault or abuse, and serious physical assault. In comparison, 185 tribal juveniles were in custody in 10 juvenile tribal facilities in 2002. (See American Indians and Crime, BJS Web, December 2004.) These tribal youth were confined mostly for misdemeanor (62%) and status offenses (29%); 10% of the youth were confined in tribal juvenile facilities for felony offenses. Table 5.3 Tribal youth admitted to the jurisdiction of the Federal Bureau of Prisons, 1999–2008 Year of commitment to BOP jurisdiction Commitment offense Total 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 2008 Total 1,909 241 252 219 234 212 231 208 164 76 72 Murder/Negligent manslaughter* 218 31 27 25 18 20 24 26 20 16 11 Assault 491 44 65 70 57 52 64 52 49 20 18 Robbery 51 7 5 9 4 7 9 4 3 1 2 Sexual abuse 441 55 52 33 65 46 55 57 40 17 21 Embezzlement 1 1 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 Burglary 442 62 66 59 61 53 43 42 30 12 14 Larceny 56 12 7 5 8 4 4 6 6 2 2 Motor vehicle theft 8 2 1 1 0 1 0 1 2 0 0 Arson and explosives 69 2 6 3 5 11 17 9 6 7 3 Other property offenses 38 13 6 6 4 1 3 3 1 1 0 Other drug felonies 3 0 1 0 0 1 0 1 0 0 0 Weapon offenses 9 1 2 0 2 1 2 1 0 0 0 Nonviolent sex offenses 36 4 4 1 4 7 7 3 5 0 1 Traffic offenses 13 2 5 1 1 3 1 0 0 0 0 Note: Total includes juveniles whose offenses were missing or unclassifiable. *Includes attempted murder. Source: Urban Institute analysis of Federal Bureau of Prisons, SENTRY data base, fiscal years 1999-2008. Compendium of Tribal Crime Data, 201142 Tribal youth served a sentence in federal facilities that was twice as long as the maximum sentence tribal facilities can impose From 1999 to 2008, the average time served by tribal youth tended to be longer (about 26 months, on average) than the tribal justice system maximum sentence of 12 months. The Tribal Law and Order Act of 2010 recently extended the maximum a tribal court can sentence to 3 years for those courts meeting conditions placed on the legal process. The average time served by non-tribal youth in BOP facilities more than doubled from 15 months in 1999 to over 38 months by 2008. Non-tribal youth admitted to the federal prison authorities were somewhat more dispersed than tribal youth with respect to district of commitment About 32% of non-tribal youth were committed from the five federal districts that committed the most tribal youth. Thirty-six percent of non-tribal youth were committed to the BOP from five federal judicial districts along the U.S.-Mexico border: California-Southern, Arizona, New Mexico, Texas-Western, and Texas-Southern. (figure 5.7). Among juveniles admitted to the jurisdiction of the BOP in 2008, non- tribal youth were slightly older at age of offense than tribal youth The average of age tribal youth at time of offense was about 15 years compared to 16 years for non-tribal youth. Most tribal youth were male (92%), American Indian (96%), non- Hispanic (99%), and United States citizens (100%). The majority of non- tribal youth were male (93%), white (60%), non-Hispanic (58%), and United States citizens (71%). 26–6026–60 10–2510–25 1–91–9 00 Number of non-tribal youth admittedNumber of non-tribal youth admitted District of Arizona (19%) New Mexico (5%) District of Western Texas (7%) District of Eastern New York (4%)District of South Dakota (3%) Figure 5.7 Non-tribal youth admitted to the jurisdiction of the Federal Bureau of Prisons, and five federal judicial districts that committed the majority of non-tribal youth, 2006–2008 Source: Based on BJS analysis of data from the Federal Bureau of Prisons, SENTRY database, fiscal years 2006–2008. Summary: Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System 43 Methodology The primary source of data presented in this report is from the Federal Justice Statistics Program (FJSP). The methodology to identify tribal youth was developed by the Urban Institute, and primary findings reported here are drawn from their 2011 study, Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System (http://ncjrs.gov). This report supplemented findings from the Urban Institute’s study with additional analyses based on BJS analysis of FJSP data. Data from the Federal Bureau of Prisons (BOP), SENTRY database, which contains information on all federally sentenced offenders admitted to BOP jurisdiction at fiscal yearend were analyzed for the years 1994 to 1998. The source of the data in figure 5.1 is The Urban Institute analysis of Executive Office for U.S. Attorneys, National LIONS database, fiscal years 2000 to 2008. Suspects in matters concluded include all matters which were concluded in each respective year. Suspects in matters prosecuted include matters for which the U.S. attorneys in that district made the decision to prosecute the matter in each fiscal year. The unit of count for figure 5.1 is the suspect matter. A matter is a referral on which an attorney spends one hour or more investigating, and on which formal papers have not been filed with the Court. If a decision is made not to continue with the investigation, it is disposed of in the LIONS database by declination and closed. References American Indians and Crime, NCJ 203097, BJS Web, December 2004. 2005 American Indian Population and Labor Force Report. U.S. Department of the Interior, Bureau of Indian Affairs, 2005. The Urban Institute. Tribal Youth in the Federal Justice System, NCJ 234549, May 2011. Available at http://ncjrs.gov. Researchers from The Urban Institute investigated how youth from Indian Country were processed by the federal criminal justice system. They used a combination of qualitative and quantitative information, including administrative data from the BJS-sponsored Federal Justice Statistics Program (FJSP) and information drawn from interviews with more than three dozen federal and tribal justice system personnel. Staff at the Urban Institute who contributed to the study included— Co-principal Investigators William Adams and Julie Samuels Contextual Analysis Team Janeen Buck Willison Hannah Dodd Meredith Dank Quantitative Analysis Team Barbara Parthasarathy Kamala Mallik Kane Jessica Kelly Sybil Mendonca KiDeuk Kim Office of Justice Programs Innovation • Partnerships • Safer Neighborhoods http://www.ojp.gov work_heeaydscafhg7hm5sgc2ihq66q ---- Northumbria Research Link Citation: Brants, Chrisje (2015) Complicated Legacies of Justice: The Netherlands and World War II. Journal of International Criminal Justice, 13 (4). pp. 763-781. ISSN 1478-1387 Published by: Oxford University Press URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/jicj/mqv050 This version was downloaded from Northumbria Research Link: http://nrl.northumbria.ac.uk/24152/ Northumbria University has developed Northumbria Research Link (NRL) to enable users to access the University’s research output. Copyright © and moral rights for items on NRL are retained by the individual author(s) and/or other copyright owners. Single copies of full items can be reproduced, displayed or performed, and given to third parties in any format or medium for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-profit purposes without prior permission or charge, provided the authors, title and full bibliographic details are given, as well as a hyperlink and/or URL to the original metadata page. The content must not be changed in any way. Full items must not be sold commercially in any format or medium without formal permission of the copyright holder. The full policy is available online: http://nrl.northumbria.ac.uk/pol i cies.html This document may differ from the final, published version of the research and has been made available online in accordance with publisher policies. To read and/or cite from the published version of the research, please visit the publisher’s website (a subscription may be required.) http://nrl.northumbria.ac.uk/policies.html 1. Complicated Legacies of Justice: The Netherlands and World War II Chrisje Brants A. Introduction After the Second World War, a process of what we now call transitional justice was initiated in the Netherlands to deal with crimes committed during the German occupation. Known as ‘extraordinary justice’ (bijzondere rechtspleging), it featured a mixture of criminal, administrative and disciplinary courts and tribunals with special jurisdiction over collaboration, treason and crimes such as murder, torture and pillage. While the deportation and murder of some 75% of the country’s Jewish population in the death camps of Eastern Europe did figure in the extraordinary courts as the background to some of the crimes, it was not the main concern. Extraordinary justice was always highly politicised, based on the assumption that the good could be clearly separated from the bad, and aimed at ridding the country of all who had made the ‘wrong choice’, i.e. sympathised or colluded with National Socialism and/or the German occupier. Focussed on what was defined as individual political criminality, it left little scope for dealing with the bystander role of the majority of the Dutch population or with such institutions as the police and civic authorities in colluding in crimes of the occupation. Moreover, the necessity of stabilising the political situation and rebuilding a devastated country meant that within ten years of the process being wound up, most Dutch perpetrators had been released and business was back to normal. At least, so it seemed, but the social division between the right and the wrong, the good and the bad, and between the main group of victims of the war, the Jews, and the rest of society was to last for decades. For those arrested and detained and/or sentenced by the extraordinary courts and tribunals, and for many others whose attitude had simply been politically incorrect, ‘normal’ meant silence. Fear of others finding out and the ostracism that would inevitably follow, precluded their participation in discussions about the war or even talking about it at home; in any event, debate was impossible in terms other than those already firmly established in public discourse. For decades too, the murder of the Dutch Jews and the trauma of the survivors were shrouded in silence. What had happened, in particular in Amsterdam (where only 10% of the Jewish population survived), and what happened afterwards to the survivors were not issues that either the Jews or the Dutch population in general cared to discuss in public – and again, often not in private either. 1 As this wall of silence was very gradually broken down from the middle of the 1960’s, the fate of Dutch Jewry became what De Haan terms a ‘national trauma’. In his 1997 book on memory and the persecution of the Jews, he recounts what happened if people asked what he was writing about: ‘Simply answering: “the persecution of the Jews”, had the same effect as announcing an incurable disease at a birthday party.’ 2 This trauma does not refer specifically to that suffered by Jewish survivors, or even to the Holocaust as such. Rather, it concerns the difficulties of dealing with the impact of the emerging facts of the Holocaust and how it unfolded in the Netherlands. Van Sas describes the sustaining collective memory of the war as a ‘myth of resistance’ in which a person could be only hero or blackguard, inherent in which is the image of right and wrong: right = resistance, wrong = collaboration; there are no in- betweens. 3 According to Blom, this memory both informed and was reinforced by Dutch historiography, of which the leading perspective was that of oppression, resistance and collaboration, good and bad. He attributes this right-wrong dichotomy to a deep-rooted consensus that can be traced back to the period immediately after the war and the process of extraordinary justice. 4 In the current transitional justice debate, law, especially criminal law, is seen as well- nigh indispensable in attaining healing for societies torn by traumatic events and for the victims of those events. We only have to look at the discourse surrounding the Internaional Criminal Court (ICC), political, legal and academic, to discover that international criminal law is assumed to help end impunity, promote retribution, reconciliation and conflict 1 On the lack of public debate: J. Withuis, Jolande, Erkenning. Van oorlogstrauma naar klaagcultuur (De Bezige Bij, 2002); A. de Swaan, De maatschappelijke verwerking van oorlogsverledens, in: J. Dane (ed.) Keerzijde van de bevrijding. Opstellen over de maatschappelijke, psycho-sociale en medische aspecten van de problematiek van oorlogsgetroffenen (Van Loghum Slaterus, 1984), at 54-66; J.H. Schreuder, Wat niet weet, wat wél deert (Radboud University Nijmegen, 1999), on the traumatic effects of silence on the second generation. Specifically on Jewish survivors: D. Hondius, Return. Holocaust Survivors and Dutch Anti-Semitism (Praeger, 2003), at 118 ff. 2 I. de Haan, Na de ondergang. De herinnering aan de Jodenvervolging in Nederland (Sdu Uitgevers, 1997), at xiii. 3 N.C.F. van Sas, De metamorfose van Nederland. Van oude orde naar moderniteit 1750-1900 (Amsterdam University Press, 2004) at 63; see also C. van der Heijden, Grijs verleden. Nederland en de Tweede Wereldoorlog (Uitgeverij Contact, 2001). 4 Blom, J.C.H. , In de ban van goed en fout. Geschiedschrijving over de bezettingstijd in Nederland (Boom, 2007) at 9-12. solution, and provide recognition of and redress for victims which will then contribute to conflict resolution, reconciliation etc. in a presumed spiral of fortunate effects. 5 Extraordinary justice in the Netherlands appears to have had much more modest aims, although in its own way it was just as ambitious (and contradictory) as international criminal law, and was in any event seen as an indispensable means of dealing with the past and reinstating social order. However, after the courts had finished, those most affected – the good, the bad and the victims – had very different perceptions of the justice that had been done, indeed of whether justice had been done at all, but their voices were often drowned out in the prevailing good-bad discourse. This contribution asks how, in the social-political context of the time, extraordinary justice coloured perceptions of events, allowing some to flourish and creating a great silence and social division around others. How did those perceptions change, and with them, the nature of public debate? With the benefit of hindsight, the legacy of extraordinary justice may help us understand more about the significance – and limits – of criminal law in processes of transition. 6 B. Extraordinary Justice It is impossible to describe in detail here the inception of extraordinary justice, the ins and outs of its procedures and its gradual development into something different from what had been envisaged. Nevertheless, in order to understand both why the latter happened and what the consequences were, we need some idea of the legal framework, the assumptions upon which it rested and how it developed in practice. 1. Assumptions and legal framework As the war progressed, the Dutch government in exile in London began thinking about what should be done with collaborators. 7 They (the Government) felt swift, severe and just action was needed to prevent mob-justice, but, dependent on reports from the Dutch resistance, had 5 See J. E. Alvarez, Trying Hussein: Between Hubris and Hegemony, Journal of International Criminal Justice (2004) 319–29, who calls these goals ‘as ambitious as they are contradictory’. 6 See the introduction by N. Wouters to: N. Wouters (ed.), Transitional Justice and Memory in Europe (1945- 2013), (Intersentia, 2014), on the importance of history for understanding processes of justice. 7 On the preparations for extraordinary justice i.a.: P. Romijn, Snel, Streng en rechtvaardig. Politiek beleid in zake de bestraffing en reclassering van ‘foute’ Nederlander 1945-1955 (De Haan, 1989), at 20; A.D. Belinfante, In plaats van bijltjesdag. De geschiedenis van de bijzondere rechtspleging na de Tweede Wereldoorlog (Van Gorcum, 1978) at 60-73; and the official Dutch war historian L. de Jong, Het koninkrijk der Nederlanden in de Tweede Wereldoorlog. IV, Londen, tweede helft (Staatsuitgeverij, 1979), at 1212-1238. no clear idea of the numbers involved nor first-hand knowledge of the situation under the occupation. The prevailing notion was that a small, perverse minority had betrayed patriotic Dutch citizens, albeit in three different ways. There were active collaborators: Dutch fascists in important administrative positions, volunteers in the German armed forces and economic profiteers. Then there were the members of the hated Dutch fascist party Nationaal Socialistische Beweging (National Socialist Movement, always known as NSB) or similar organizations, collaborators by definition because of their politics. And finally there were treasonous or unreliable civil servants and government employees. All these people were manifestly ‘on the wrong side’ and there would, so declared Queen Wilhelmina, be no place for them in free Dutch society. 8 These seriously oversimplified assumptions about the actual situation implied both that ‘right’ and ‘wrong’ were easily distinguishable in practice and that everyone who had not openly made the wrong choice must therefore have made the right one. They were translated into a legal framework corresponding to the three groups presumed to have behaved ‘wrongly’. 9 The Decree on Extraordinary Criminal Law of 22 December 1943 10 concerned serious, active collaboration, adding to the relevant provisions of the existing Dutch Criminal Code the offences of ‘collaboration with the enemy’ and ‘betrayal’ (essentially subjecting another person to measures by the enemy) with a maximum of five years imprisonment; if a victim had died as a result, the penalty was life imprisonment or death. In 1947, war crimes were added to allow the trial of German citizens. Another decree regulated procedural matters, including new extraordinary trial courts and an extraordinary supreme court staffed by professional judges. 11 The Decree on Purging the Administration 12 created a disciplinary regime for civil servants and government employees who had ‘demonstrated a treasonable attitude’, or could 8 Speech by Queen Wilhelmina, Free Dutch Radio (Radio Oranje), broadcast from London, 10 May 1941. In later years, she spoke several times again of ‘swift, severe and just retribution’ and of isolating and removing all ‘undesirable elements’. 9 For details of disciplinary and criminal law: W.M.E.Noach, De bijzondere rechtspleging. Straf- en tuchtrechtelijk optreden tegen onvaderlandslievend gedrag uit de bezettingsjaren, (Martinus Nijhoff, 1948); Belinfante, supra note 7; L. de Jong, Het koninkrijk der Nederlanden in de Tweede Wereldoorlog: deel 12 Epiloog, eerste helft, (Martinus Nijhoff 1988); Administrative cleansing is described by Romijn, supra note 7, at 79-162. For an overview in English: C.H. Brants, Dealing with the Holocaust and Collaboration: the Dutch Experience of Criminal Justice and Accountability after World War 2, 33 Crime, Law and Social Change 3 (2000) 211-236. 10 Besluit Buitengewoon Strafrecht 22 December 1943, Staatsblad D61. 11 Besluit Buitengewone Rechtspleging 22 December 1943, Staatsblad D 63; Besluit Bijzondere Gerechtshoven, 22 December 1943, Staatsblad D 62. 12 Zuiveringsbesluit 13 January 1944, Staatsblad E 14. http://www.google.com/url?q=http%3A%2F%2Fwetten.overheid.nl%2FBWBR0002008%2Fgeldigheidsdatum_23-12-2009&sa=D&sntz=1&usg=AFrqEzfJjOI5A_6xFYCqQHAQx_Tm3jxdSA http://www.google.com/url?q=http%3A%2F%2Flexius.nl%2Fbesluit-op-de-bijzondere-gerechtshoven&sa=D&sntz=1&usg=AFrqEzcLTk530iT27d38t6ZLRx5fEb1t2Q http://www.google.com/url?q=http%3A%2F%2Flexius.nl%2Fbesluit-op-de-bijzondere-gerechtshoven&sa=D&sntz=1&usg=AFrqEzcLTk530iT27d38t6ZLRx5fEb1t2Q ‘not be relied upon to faithfully co-operate in rebuilding the country’. 13 Sanctions were suspension (with salary) or dishonourable discharge (with loss of salary and, in some cases, pension rights). This group was dealt with by a ‘Central Organ’, but there were also separate commissions that examined the war record of numerous different professions (journalists, university teachers, artists etc.). Finally, a Decree on Tribunals 14 dealt with all Dutch citizens ‘who, during the course of hostilities or of the occupation of the Kingdom of the Netherlands, have behaved in a way that is abhorrent to every good patriot.’ This could be anything, from assisting the enemy to displaying a ‘national-socialist attitude’. 15 The lay tribunals, under a professional chairman, could impose one of three penalties: ten years internment, the withdrawal of civil rights or confiscation of property. This disciplinary law was to culminate with extraordinary criminal proceedings, making double jeopardy the norm. Indeed, government employees and other professionals could be subject to all three forms of justice. These decrees contained vague, multi-interpretable and overlapping provisions and contravened the Dutch Constitution and existing criminal law principles: retro-active criminalisation, the death penalty (abolished in the 19th century), lay judges (forbidden by the Dutch Constitution), the confiscation of a person’s entire assets and denial of civil rights (the outlawed Napoleonic practice of ‘civil death’); 16 no appeal on the facts, while appeal to the extraordinary supreme court on points of law depended on permission by the trial court. 17 The tribunals judged cases brought by members of the public without a public prosecutor on whom the onus of proof rested. 2. Unforeseen Practicalities and the Solutions Almost immediately after liberation it was obvious that far too many people were caught up in a system not yet ready to operate (too few high-ranking and respected judges were available 18 and some prospective chairmen objected to the law they would apply, especially mandatory sentencing). Between 120,000 and 150,000 people, some probably innocent, many 13 Idem Article 3, para.1 14 Tribunaalbesluit, 17 September 1944, Staatsblad E101. 15 Noach supra, note 9, at 57. 16 While by today’s standards the culmination of trial by tribunal and criminal court and of the sanctions that both could impose, would be inadmissible, at the time Dutch legal scholars were divided on the matter of double jeopardy. 17 Under normal Dutch criminal procedure, there is a right to full re-trial by a higher court and to appeal to the Supreme Court on points of law. 18 With some exceptions, the higher Dutch judiciary had not acquitted itself with particular distinction during the occupation; see D. Venema, Rechters in oorlogstijd (Boom Juridische uitgevers 2007). suspected of very minor offences, had been arrested and detained. 19 There was no habeas corpus and a serious backlog of judicial cases. Severe overcrowding, food shortages, ill treatment and even torture plagued some detention camps. Within months, the Government was forced to reduce the numbers by releasing minor cases, 20 then, when more releases had to be contemplated, by changing the definition of a ‘minor case’. Once the legal process was underway, procedural rules were held to be unjust and unworkable and this too led to delays and then substantial amendments that changed the nature of the envisaged ‘swift, just and severe retribution’. The Government, however, was not only moved by practical considerations. Social and political protest by authoritative figures about conditions in the camps and the harshness of the legal rules were gradually picked up by the media. The churches, particularly the Catholic Church, appealed urgently to Christian compassion, irreconcilable with ‘eliminating people from society’. 21 After the release of 40,000 ‘minor cases’, the churches again called for compassion. Although the intended release of another 60,000 (the definition of ‘minor’ having been extended) led to widespread public protest, 22 by May 1947 more than 100,000 people had been set free. Combined with the introduction of habeas corpus for political detainees, this left about 3,000 by 1 October 1948. The release of ‘political delinquents’ (even if their guilt was not always officially determined), 23 was often conditional on supervision by a new organisation, the STPD (Stichting Toezicht Politieke Delinquenten – Foundation for the Supervision of Political Delinquents). A private initiative with government subsidy and staffed mainly by volunteers, it supervised but also supported convicted and non-convicted ‘political delinquents’ with the aim of helping them return to society. It too was vocal in its support of release policies and amendments to the court and tribunal process. 24 Tribunals were soon allowed to deviate from mandatory sentencing that was withdrawn altogether in 1946. In 1947, more flexible penalties were introduced and double 19 In general it is impossible to give exact figures for the process of extraordinary justice. The first weeks were chaotic and not properly documented. The files were not generally available for research until relatively recently. Publications show that some files are missing, double, or contain more than one case. See e.g. S. Faber and G. Donker, Bijzonder Gewoon. Het Centraal Archief Bijzondere rechtspleging (1944-2000) en de lichte gevallen (3rd edn., Stichting moderne Rechtsgeschiedenis, 2010). 20 Besluit Politieke Delinquenten 26 October 1945, Staatsblad F244. 21 De Haan, supra note 2, at 90 ff. 22 Noach, supra note 9, at 16-17. 23 Belinfante (supra note 7, at 76) thinks it a measure of how well the release policy worked that, of those who later appeared before an extraordinary court, only 1.25% was found to have been wrongfully arrested. The other side of the coin is that many detainees were, therefore, probably innocent. 24 See on the Foundation’s work: J. le Poole, Verslag der werkzaamheden van de Stichting Toezicht Politieke Delinquenten over de jaren 1945 t/m 1947 (s.e., 1948). http://www.archieven.nl/nl/zoeken?mivast=0&mizig=210&miadt=298&miaet=1&micode=870&minr=1786874&miq=561706033&miview=inv2&milang=nl http://www.archieven.nl/nl/zoeken?mivast=0&mizig=210&miadt=298&miaet=1&micode=870&minr=1786874&miq=561706033&miview=inv2&milang=nl http://www.geheugenvannederland.nl/?/nl/items/EVDO02:NIOD05_8240/&st=toezicht%20delinquenten&sc=%28cql.serverChoice%20all%20toezicht%20%20AND%20delinquenten%29&singleitem=true jeopardy abolished, thereby legalising what had already become practice: less serious cases tried by tribunals only, serious criminal offences by extraordinary courts where there was now an automatic right of appeal on points of law i.a. if the death penalty had been imposed. The purging process also underwent substantive changes, most importantly perhaps because the country would come to a standstill if too many were removed from their jobs. At an early stage, more flexible sanctions and differentiation between categories of seriousness were introduced: ‘mistakes’ during the war could result in a caution (public or non-public) or demotion; less serious cases were punishable by honourable discharge with no loss of pension rights, and minor cases by demotion; the original decree remained applicable to serious cases only. In total, after release of the minor cases, the courts and tribunals dealt with approximately 65,000 people, 8% of whom were acquitted, with 16% receiving fines, 60% sentences of more than five years, 9% between five and ten years, and 3% between ten and 15 years; 578 people were sentenced to more than fifteen years, 148 to life and 152 to death of whom 40 were executed. 25 By 1964, all of the convicted Dutch citizens were free. Most government employees who had been dismissed were rehabilitated by the beginning of the 1950’s, successfully campaigning in 1956 for restoration of their pension rights. 3. From Collective to Individual Retribution The decrees on extraordinary justice and purging the administration were intended as a system of collective retribution, but the simplistic notion on which they were based – that within the three different ‘wrong’ groups, all were equally culpable – bore little resemblance to the variations in war-time behaviour. As the legal process went on, it became clear that more scope for individual differentiation was needed. Procedural amendments helped, but the finer shades of distinction are to be found in the sentencing practices through which collective justice evolved into individual justice. At the same time, the idea that everyone should (let alone could) be tried faded into the background, although the underlying reasons differ between the purge and the process of administrative and criminal justice. Not all supported the collective purge of the Dutch administration: some thought a public servant should remain at his post in ‘the interests of the country’, 26 others objected to 25 These figures are provided by P. Romijn and Eric Schumacher, Transitional Justice in the Netherlands after World War II, in: N. Wouters (ed.), Transitional Justice and Memory in Europe (1945-2013) (Intersentia 2014), at 133-171. 26 De Haan, supra note 2, at 89-94. what they saw as discrimination of the ‘little man’ while the big shots got off. 27 There were indeed large discrepancies in the punishment meted out to civil servants and government employees caught up in the purge (about 10% of the total), among them very high-ranking officials such as mayors and chiefs of police; some were dishonourably discharged and prosecuted, others not. 28 Moreover, the idea of a collective purge of the ideologically unsound contradicted the reality of an administration under occupation. All who remained in government employment by definition co-operated with enemy, but seldom as intentional collaborators or traitors: there were active collaborators; there were also heroes who sabotaged the enemy’s work; the great majority simply got on with the job. Dealing with the highest officials who had remained in office until the very end soon overshadowed the purge of minor employees that gradually ground to a halt. Romijn attributes this to the power struggle between the new and old elite, it being imperative for the latter that purging the administration did not become a divisive political issue. 29 But there were also considerations of just retribution, of not blaming the lower ranks for following the example of their superiors and of making sure that individual circumstances were taken into account. The individualisation of sanctions was even more apparent in extraordinary criminal and administrative justice, 30 where sentences gradually became less harsh, most noticeably at the extraordinary courts. The maximum penalty for joining enemy forces, for example, was death, and some death sentences were passed and executed. Over time, courts came to distinguish between the Waffen SS (regarded as most reprehensible) and other branches of the German forces, took into account the youthful age of most volunteers who, after 1947, were no longer prosecuted, and brought the sentence for Waffen-SS’ers down to between eight and 15 years. While it is less easy to discover clear sentencing patterns for the other capital offences, betrayal and collaboration, here too sentences for even very serious crimes became more lenient as the courts discovered that, however immoral a person’s behaviour and horrific the consequences, there was always some case that was worse. Eventually, the notion of collective justice was entirely abandoned as courts sought to ensure that the punishment fitted the individual crime. Although the consequences of many acts of betrayal were the same (the victims died), there were obviously different circumstances, motives and degrees of blame. In 1945, one 27 Romijn, supra note 7, at 20. 28 De Haan, supra note 7, at 88-89; Romijn, supra note 7, at 143 ff. 29 Romijn, supra note 7, at 95-109 30 The following is based on Belinfante, supra note 7, ch. IX-XII. incident and the death of one person could lead to a death sentence. Later, the death penalty was rare. In 1949, for example, a Dutch ‘businessman’ who conned several Jews into paying to be ‘smuggled to England’ then handed them over to the Germans, was sentenced to 15 years in prison. 31 Public officials who had merely done their job did not appear before the extraordinary courts. Only those who had been more than enthusiastic in assisting the occupying forces were prosecuted, with police officers who had hunted down Jews in hiding or betrayed resistance workers receiving harsh sentences until the very end. It was also clear that severe penalties for low-ranking employees or policemen were problematic considering the bad example often given by superiors. 32 However, even when the perpetrators were mayors, individualisation and mitigation in sentencing became the norm over the years, although the courts continued to regard NSB-membership as an aggravating factor. In 1945, for example, the NSB-mayor of Wassenaar was sentenced to life (later commuted to 20 years, although his actions had not had any dire results. Three years later, the mayor of Amsterdam, not a member of the NSB, received three years; his NSB-colleague in The Hague, 12; the mayor of Rotterdam, a considerably more active collaborator than either of the others, got ten years. The great majority of Dutch Jews had been deported under their leadership. Most difficult were the cases of the ‘good’ mayors, who had been appointed before the war and had never sympathized with national-socialism. They too had sometimes delivered Jews into the hands of the Germans. After consideration of the circumstances, they got off sometimes very lightly. 4. A Policy of Pardons In 1950, the process of extraordinary justice gradually came to an end. A 1949 parliamentary inquiry commission examined the role of government under the occupation but decided the part played by high-ranking civil servants who had ‘looked after the country’s affairs’ after the government fled to London, did not really come under its mandate; it did no more than state that ‘some civil servants were insufficiently aware of where to draw the line’. 33 Then, while the extraordinary courts were still sitting, the Government embarked on a policy of pardons. Partly a response to public opinion where vengeful feelings had somewhat subsided (though not towards the Germans), and to pleas for clemency by the churches and 31 Belinfante, supra note 7, at 372. 32 ‘[I]n many branches of the police force, we find the most serious offences … committed by the highest ranking officers…and what is worse, by shifting the burden of their responsibility as superiors onto their subordinates to whom fell the actual dirty work…We also find poignant discrepancies in the sentencing of such cases (Extraordinary Supreme Court, 8 November 1948). 33 De Haan, supra note 2, at 91. authoritative legal scholars, above all the policy of pardons was driven by socio-political and economic considerations. The country was devastated, the population split by memories of the war; rebuilding a stable society and viable economy was impossible without reconciliation and thus reintegration of political delinquents. Enough was enough. In 1947, discrepancies in sentencing that came to light on appeal to the Extraordinary Supreme Court were resolved by commuting harsh sentences imposed immediately after the war. 1948, Queen Wilhelmina’s jubilee year, saw the first of several mass pardons. The first youthful volunteers were pardoned in 1949, soon followed by the older ones. In 1950, pardons were issued for all those with ten years still to serve, later followed by a commission to look into cases with 15 years remaining. Then in 1951, lifers began to be pardoned. In the following years, increasing numbers of prisoners were pardoned and freed, among them 67 who had originally received death sentences. 34 C. Perceptions of Justice and Legacies of Silence Already while extraordinary justice was ongoing, and certainly afterwards, there was a festering pool of dissatisfaction that was to flare up in public debate in the years to come. 35 But the specific groups concerned – ex-resistance fighters, Jewish survivors and collaborators – were different, and so too the reasons for their disillusionment. It was partly the legal process itself that led to perceptions that justice had not been done, but this cannot be separated from its socio-political context. These different perceptions, deriving from very different experiences of the war, were not equally represented in public discourse; some were silenced for many years, only to emerge as the respective groups found a voice and the nature of public debate gradually changed. 1. The Resistance Those directly and professionally involved or interested (government ministers, judges, legal scholars and practitioners, academics), in short the old elite, felt that extraordinary justice had been a success once the practical problems were solved. But a substantial part of public opinion as represented in the now legal war-time underground press, the new political parties 34 Because there had been public unease about executing the death penalty given that it could not be appealed, by March 1946 death sentences were not carried out anyway unless the Crown had considered a pardon. Those remaining were eventually all commuted to life. 35 Romijn and Schumacher, supra note 25, at 151. striving for power and especially ex-members of the resistance saw the policy of releasing so many from detention, the extension of the definition of ‘minor cases’ in 1945-1946, the increasingly lenient sentences and the pardons as unwarranted leniency. ‘…The law must have its course…Those who dispense justice should know that they are subjecting our people to a new crime if they hesitate to punish the guilty…we do not ask for the hangman, but for justice according to honour and conscience.’ 36 It is unknown who wrote this, but it neatly sums up feelings of many resistance members, part of the new elite, who were highly critical of the policies of the old governing parties, including the way extraordinary justice was handled and the (political) compassion that guided its course. Twenty five years later, after the publication of what is still the classic study on extraordinary justice, 37 ex-resistance fighter (and criminologist) Willem Nagel was unable to hide the anger he had felt at the time. Writing under his pen name, J.B. Charles, he exclaimed: ‘Has it taken until 1978 for us to be shocked by the compassion that poisoned the so-called justice of 1945?’ 38 This concept of ‘compassion’ has been explained as the expression of a predominantly catholic moral, exceedingly useful for the powerful catholic party that formed part of the first post-war coalition governments and also provided the prime-minister. A number of authors see extraordinary justice in this framework. 39 Compassion was a way of depoliticizing the issue – an appeal to fundamental Christian values not easily opposed politically – and, with it, the Resistance whose members became the war heroes of yesterday, not the political heroes of today. Resistance in the Netherlands did not really come into its own until halfway through the war. However, those who resisted the Germans from the outset were almost all politically motivated and organized accordingly. The largest group arose from the communist party, while others organized around socialist and/or pacifist leaders. The other significant group came from the Dutch reformed church. Their common ground was a desire for a new order after liberation, though they differed on what should constitute that order. This was a politically destabilizing factor in post-war society and the governing elite were keen to prevent the Resistance as such becoming a political group. Being silenced as a political force, however, is not the same as silence about the role of the Resistance. 36 Anonymous pamphlet, Archives NIOD Doc II 249, no. 0127C-49. 37 Namely Belinfante, supra note 7. 38 J.B. Charles, Van het kleine koude front (7th edn., Amsterdam 1984). 39 Romijn, supra note 7, De Haan, supra note 2. Immediately after the war, there was much public interest in the resistance and several ex-members published widely-read memoirs. 40 These set the tone for a discourse of patriotic heroism, 41 reinforced in 1947 by the award of pensions for members of the former Resistance and their families. Hondius refers to a ‘new social hierarchy’ formed in the reaction after the war: resistance fighters at the top, collaborators at the bottom … a hierarchy [that] was widely accepted and has remained in place and essentially unchanged since 1945’. 42 But while this informed the myth of resistance, one group was excluded: the communist ex- resistance, whom the cold war pushed down the social hierarchy and deprived of the authority their war record conferred. Paradoxically, while the Resistance was depoliticised, discussions about the war were conducted in the distinctly politicised, ideological frame of democracy versus totalitarianism. What was not needed in that context, were personal stories of injustice, precisely what Jewish survivors needed to tell. 43 2. Jewish Survivors The voice of Jewish survivors recently returned from the camps or re-emerging from hiding was barely heard after the war. In so far as they were directly concerned with extraordinary justice, they, or their now dead family members, were simply individual victims. The process had not done justice to the experience of genocide, but this was something they could not articulate. In the prevailing discourse, Jews were no different from anyone else who survived the war, a reflection of a strict government policy of neutrality: no single category of war victims was to be favoured above others. ‘Collective victimisation’, 44 however, hid the fact that a tragedy had befallen the Jews that was of a different order to what had happened to the Dutch as a nation, even during the horrendous final year of starvation, lack of fuel and an increasingly brutal occupation, during which thousands died. This ‘hunger winter’ also fed the population’s perception of collective victimisation: granted, the Jews were in camps but we ate tulip bulbs or starved. 40 J.C.H. Blom, I. Schöffer and A.C. 't Hart, De affaire-Menten, 1945-1976: eindrapport van de Commissie van Onderzoek betreffende het opsporingsbeleid inzake Menten vanaf de bevrijding tot de zomer van 1976 en de invloeden waaraan dat beleid al dan niet heeft blootgestaan (Staatsuitgeverij, 1979) at 191-192. 41 J. Bank, Oorlogsverleden in Nederland (Ambo, 1983) at 8-9. 42 Hondius, supra note 1, at 160/161. 43 Ismee Tames & Jolande Withuis, Stilte na de oorlog?, 9 Historisch Nieuwsblad (2010), 68-75. 44 Romijn and Schumacher, supra note 25, at 149. There was also no distinction in support for victims, which was temporary and scarce, the exception being pensions for ex-resistance members. Jewish survivors felt betrayed – yet again – on returning to the Netherlands, 45 where they met indifference and sometimes hostility at the borders and in the cities where their own community no longer existed, and struggled to recover confiscated or (mis)appropriated property. In some cases, non-Jewish neighbours refused to return goods entrusted to them for safe-keeping, even expressing open displeasure that the rightful owner had returned alive. 46 More than anything, there was lack of understanding: the Jews should stop whining, be grateful for what they had and get on with their life. In the midst of what was at best indifference to the particular nature of their experience, traumatised Jewish survivors were unwilling and afraid to manifest themselves as such. This silence was finally broken after 20 years. More important in the Dutch context than the trial of Adolf Eichmann (although that led to shock and disbelief), was the television series De Bezetting (The Occupation), a prequel to official historian L. de Jong’s magnus opum on the Netherlands during World War II. On May 3 1962, the episode on the persecution, deportation and murder of the Dutch Jews stunned the audience and the media. De Jong encouraged another Jewish historian, J. Presser, to write a specific history of the Jews during the occupation. 47 Ondergang (Downfall) appeared in 1965, a harrowing tale of exclusion and destruction. Then, at the beginning of the 1970’s, reports began to appear on ‘concentration camp syndrome’ and in 1972, a television documentary about a psychiatrist and his Jewish patients (Begrijp je nu waarom ik huil? – Now do you understand why I weep?), drove home the reality of living with memories of the Holocaust. Jewish survivors now had a voice, raised that same year in public protest against granting pardons to the last remaining – German – prisoners serving life sentences (the so- called Three of Breda). Many academics and clergy supported release – and for the same reason: life imprisonment is inhumane. But anti-release groups were vociferous and shared a different sentiment: to release these Germans is to inflict yet more suffering on their victims. Such was the public outcry that, after an emotional parliamentary debate, the pardons were refused. A year later, when Jewish victim-survivors were specifically compensated (Wet Uitkering Vervolgingsslachtoffers – Law on Support of Victims of Persecution), this was 45 D. Hondius, The persistence of uneasiness: Dutch Jews and non-Jews since 1945 (unpublished manuscript held by National Institute for Holocaust Studies - NIOD, Amsterdam, 1998); Hondius, supra note 1. See also M. Citroen, U wordt door niemand verwacht. Nederlandse Joden na kampen en onderduik (Het Spectrum, 1999). 46 The title of Citroen’s book (note 45 supra) in English is: Nobody is expecting you. Dutch Jews emerging from the camps and hiding. 47 J. Presser, Ondergang. De vervolging en verdelging van het Nederlandse Jodendom, 1940-1945 (Nijhoff, 1965). justified as an act of special solidarity on the part of the Dutch population. 48 The Germans (now two, one died in prison) were not released until 1989; both died shortly afterwards in Germany. 3. Collaborators Despite the releases and pardons, the efforts of the STPD that latterly had functioned as a reintegration service for political delinquents, and the political stress on rebuilding the country, the reconciliatory ideas of political and social elites were not shared by the population in general. 49 This was partly due to dissatisfaction with extraordinary justice, but there was also anger at the support and housing collaborators received while victims struggled to make ends meet amid a general housing shortage. The STPD noted that many ex- political delinquents found it impossible to find jobs, were shunned by neighbours and that their children were discriminated against by friends and even teachers. 50 In later years, the group was no longer categorically rejected, but their position was difficult enough for them to shroud their past in protective silence. At the same time, many were also angry about the treatment meted out in the first months after liberation and their children grew up in an atmosphere of silent bitterness. Early attempts to break the silence were met with hostility and disbelief. In 1949, a Dutch fascist published a report on the detention camps, detailing the ill-treatment, starvation rations, torture and even murder of detainees. 51 Although some were shocked, the more so since the facts were corroborated by less suspect sources, 52 the Government took steps to improve the situation and the fuss died away. Only recently has there been serious and detailed research into what happened in this ‘forgotten past’ (the subtitle of one such publication). 53 As to the fact of collaboration, in 1967 the first attempt to throw some light on who the collaborators were and what their motives, 54 met with a storm of criticism especially 48 At the end of the century, when the details emerged of how the Jews had been looted by official Dutch institutions, government, stock-market, banks and insurance companies donated a combined 764 million guilders (Romijn and Schumacher, supra note 25, at 164). 49 Romijn and Schumacher, supra note 25, at 159. 50 Le Poole, supra note 24, at 11-12. 51 H.W. van der Vaart Smit, Kamptoestanden 1944/`45-1948 – rapport (Keizerskroon, 1949). 52 A. van Liempt, Na de bevrijding. De loodzware jaren 1945-1950 (Uitgeverij Balans, 2014), at 47 53 G. Abuys, and Bas Kortholt, Interneringskamp Westerbork: verhalen van een vergeten verleden (1945-1948) (Just Publishers, 2010); see also R. Hoving, Het foute kamp. De geschiedenis van het Amersfoortse interneringskamp Laan 1914 (1945-1946) (Donker, 2011). 54 Armando en H. Sleutelaar, De SS’ers. Nederlandse vrijwilligers in de Tweede Wereldoorlog, (De Bezige Bij,1967). from papers that were a continuation of the underground press. Even in the 1980’s studies of collaborators received little general attention. 55 Collaborators had always been reluctant to seek a public platform. In 1947, a number of leading ex-NSB members had apologized publicly, but this admission of guilt was not taken seriously and there were no more large scale attempts. 56 According to Tames, while reintegration was certainly not easy and there was no real reconciliation, things were not as bad in practice as the right-wrong discourse would suggest; collaborators were ‘allowed’ back, but only in so far as they were prepared to admit their fundamental guilt, making them ever dependent on the conditional good will of others. 57 Their children formed a particularly difficult and vulnerable group, who, for obvious reasons, were both traumatized by the silence and/or the knowledge of who their parents were, and yet could not speak out of loyalty or fear, or both. During the 1980’s, they were grudgingly but not widely recognised as one of the groups for whom the war had brought specific traumas. 58 It is, however, only in the past ten years that their individual stories have started to be told. 59 D. The bystander role of the Dutch population If the three specifically dissatisfied groups were eventually able to articulate their feelings, until the end of the millennium neither they nor anyone else managed to put the one subject enduringly smothered by the myth of resistance on the agenda of public debate: the bystander role of the great majority of Dutch citizens. Writing on protests against ‘lenient’ justice, the director of the STDP noted: ‘So many compatriots bear some moral guilt, because … they refused to help those in need. The more they proclaim they were “anti”, though in reality “neutral”, during the occupation, the louder they are after liberation!’ 60 Years later and after the Three of Breda affair, a legal scholar noted: ‘…the settling of accounts for what happened to the Jews … should include the culpable negligence of the Dutch. If solidarity with victims 55 E.g. J. Hofman, De collaborateur. Een sociaal-psychologisch onderzoek naar misdadig gedrag in dienst van de Duitse bezetter (Boom, 1981), and H. Stouten, Naar verkeerd spoor. Achtergronden van Nederlandse politieke delinquenten, 1940-1945 (Stubeg 1986); the latter, a prison director had waited 40 years to publish his experiences because he felt his ideas did not fit the prevailing consensus on the war. 56 Romijn & Schumacher, supra note 25, at 167/168. 57 I. Tames, Doorn in het vlees. Foute Nederlanders in de jaren vijftig en zestig (Balans, 2013). 58 H.J. Scheffel-Baars, Kind van foute ouders (Werkgroep Herkenning, 1984). 59 See e.g B. Kromhout, Fout geboren: het verhaal van kinderen van foute ouders (Contact, 2004); C. van der Heijden, Kinderen van foute ouders: hun verhaal, (Uitgeverij Atlas Contact, 2014). 60 Le Poole, supra note 24, at 23. http://opac-gonext.oclc.org:8180/DB=8/SET=5/TTL=6/REL?PPN=069183449 http://opac-gonext.oclc.org:8180/DB=8/SET=5/TTL=6/CLK?IKT=4&TRM=Kind http://opac-gonext.oclc.org:8180/DB=8/SET=5/TTL=6/CLK?IKT=4&TRM=foute http://opac-gonext.oclc.org:8180/DB=8/SET=5/TTL=6/CLK?IKT=4&TRM=ouders http://opac-gonext.oclc.org:8180/DB=8/SET=5/TTL=2/CLK?IKT=4&TRM=Fout http://opac-gonext.oclc.org:8180/DB=8/SET=5/TTL=2/CLK?IKT=4&TRM=geboren http://opac-gonext.oclc.org:8180/DB=8/SET=5/TTL=2/CLK?IKT=4&TRM=verhaal http://opac-gonext.oclc.org:8180/DB=8/SET=5/TTL=2/CLK?IKT=4&TRM=kinderen http://opac-gonext.oclc.org:8180/DB=8/SET=5/TTL=2/CLK?IKT=4&TRM=foute http://opac-gonext.oclc.org:8180/DB=8/SET=5/TTL=2/CLK?IKT=4&TRM=ouders http://opac-gonext.oclc.org:8180/DB=8/SET=5/TTL=7/CLK?IKT=4&TRM=Kinderen http://opac-gonext.oclc.org:8180/DB=8/SET=5/TTL=7/CLK?IKT=4&TRM=foute http://opac-gonext.oclc.org:8180/DB=8/SET=5/TTL=7/CLK?IKT=4&TRM=ouders http://opac-gonext.oclc.org:8180/DB=8/SET=5/TTL=7/CLK?IKT=4&TRM=hun http://opac-gonext.oclc.org:8180/DB=8/SET=5/TTL=7/CLK?IKT=4&TRM=verhaal is enforced through punishing the Three of Breda, extraordinary justice becomes an alibi for all those only too keen to pass their own failings and blame to the Germans.’ 61 Then, as before, there was little room for such soul searching. Right versus wrong defined the war years from the beginning, continually reinforced in the writings of historians such as de Jong and Presser, 62 and by sporadic revelations that public figures had been ‘wrong’ during the war. After one such incident, the then Dutch Prime Minister Lubbers wrote in a private letter: ‘The image this society…has of the war is totally out of focus. “You were right or you were wrong”. The reality of grey is completely ignored.’ 63 That grey reality is now the subject of much new research, following a call by Blom to move forward from the right-wrong dichotomy. Why the persecution of the Jews was so catastrophic in the Netherlands has become a pressing question for historians: the Dutch paradox, for were not the Jews always received with great tolerance? 64 Yet, of all Western European countries, the Netherlands lost the greatest percentage of its Jewish population (75%, as opposed to 25% in France, for example, and 40% in Belgium). There have many explanations as to why the Dutch Jews fared so badly. Obviously, the Netherlands has no wild countryside (as in France) and bordered no neutral country to which to escape (as did Denmark). More importantly, deportations in the Netherlands were uninterrupted and less violent than elsewhere, while the Jewish Council continued to cooperate till the end. The Jews of the Netherlands were highly assimilated and ‘clung to the legal options which then proved to be part of the deportation system’. 65 This is with the benefit of hindsight, and so too are explanations as to why the majority and the Dutch administration were so compliant. According to Romijn, protecting the population at large, not its most vulnerable group, was the authorities’ priority. In the mixture of force and deceit that the Germans employed, tolerating discrimination of the Jews seemed wiser than protest. But this was a slippery slope and these ‘politics of lesser evil’ became bankrupt by 1943 when the Germans turned their attention to the Dutch population itself, and evading forced labour in Germany became the acceptable reaction (although many did go). 61 C.H.F. Rüter, Enkele aspecten van de strafrechtelijke reactie op oorlogsmisdrijven en misdrijven tegen de menselijkheid (University Press Amsterdam, 1973), at 147. 62 Blom, supra note 4; Van der Heijden, supra note 3, at 410. 63 Quoted in R. Bouwman, De val van een bergredenaar (Boom, 2000), at 319. 64 Blom, supra note 4, at 75; this book combines i.a. two inaugural speeches. It is in the first (at 9-30), given in 1983, that he makes his appeal for recognising shades of grey. 65 P. Griffioen and R. Zeller, Comparing the persecution of the Jews in the Netherlands, France and Belgium, 1940-1945: similarities, differences, causes, in: The Persecution of the Jews in the Netherlands, 1940-1945. New Perspectives (Vossiuspers UvA, 2012), at 77-78. This attitude on the part of the (highest) authorities partly explains why, when public servants were required to sign the ‘declaration of Aryan descent’, only seven non-Jews in the whole country refused, or why the gradual exclusion of Jews from public life went ahead so smoothly. 66 When the razzias started in February 1941, there was brief and violent public protest in Amsterdam led by communist dockers (the ‘February Strike’); it was put down harshly, but made the Germans more circumspect in rounding up Jews for deportation. Van der Heijden points out that there was comparatively little resistance until 1943 and that armed resistance was also less than in other countries. He puts the compliance of the population down to an inclination to compromise, obedience to authority and trust in the administration. 67 But hindsight now begs the question of what people knew then. Private diaries from the period show that many were distressed by what was happening to the Jews (if also mildly anti-Semitic) but that they did not understand its significance, despite the stories about destruction and extermination in ‘the East’ as broadcast via the BBC and underground press. 68 While Van der Heijden also doubts how much people knew, the main gist of his study is that the ‘grey, middle-of-the-road position of the bystander’ made it was easier to avoid trouble and adapt to an increasingly difficult reality. Historians are coming to see this as a continuation of pre-war social and political relations: the capacity of both administration and population to adapt derives from a political culture of accommodation that made contact and cooperation with the Germans possible without its necessarily being (perceived as) collaboration. 69 Part of the Dutch paradox, this also goes some way to explaining the myth of resistance and the great silence that shrouded first the fate of the Jews and later, when the facts were known, the role the Dutch themselves had played in it. Withuis stresses that, because the experience and significance of the war and post-war situation differed for different groups, it was impossible to find a collective narrative for the future. The failure to protect the Jews is hardly a candidate, especially not in a country that regards itself as extremely tolerant. And so the narrative evolved towards oppression and heroic resistance. The more this is emphasised, however, the more the decidedly unheroic attitude towards the deportations must be denied, notions of ‘right’ and ‘wrong’ dominate the debate and, where 66 P. Romijn, The ‘Lesser Evil’ – the case of the Dutch local authorities and the Holocaust, in: The Persecution of the Jews in the Netherlands, 1940-1945. New Perspectives (Vossiuspers UvA, 2012) 13-28 at 17-19. 67 Van der Heijden, supra note 3, at 287. 68 B. van der Boom, ‘Wij weten niets van hun lot’. Gewone Nederlanders en de Holocaust (Boom, 2012). (The title, a quote from a diary, is worth translating: ‘We know nothing of their fate’). 69 Blom, supra note 4). silence reigns in the absence of a narrative that all can share, post-war traumas are medicalised rather than treated as social problems. 70 The new historiography has created a narrative something akin to collective guilt for what happened to the Jews, both during and after the war; there is more understanding of the role of so-called collaborators 71 and certainly of the difficulties their children faced (although to have been the child of ‘wrong’ parents is a stigma most would prefer to avoid, even today). Interestingly, as this new truth, ‘the guilty Dutch’, took hold, studies of the resistance celebrating its heroes began to appear as if to ward off the risk that their memory would succumb to the weight of collective responsibility. 72 E. Conclusion With the exception of what happened in the detention camps, the unofficial reaction to collaborators was fairly mild in the Netherlands, certainly in comparison with, say, France. In that, extraordinary justice was certainly successful. But it was also inevitably flawed, procedurally, but perhaps more importantly, as a social process. The courts struggled with the realization that the stark categories of right and wrong had only some link with reality and that collective justice was therefore no justice at all, and did their best to provide fair trial and punishment in the individual circumstances. That this was viewed as too lenient was exacerbated by the release and pardon policies. Yet, leniency and ‘compassion’ cannot simply be dismissed as part of the political struggle of the time. A measure of due process, establishing individual guilt, proportional sentencing, some degree of equality through mitigation of the harsh sentences of the early years, releasing minor cases and attempting to prevent the perpetual exclusion from society of those found wanting, were not merely pragmatic-political issues but justifiable concerns of judges, legal scholars and government wrestling with the question: what is just retribution in such extraordinary circumstances? Knowing what we know now, it seems extraordinary indeed that the whole process was premised on the ideological-political distinction of right and wrong, so that the offences specifically designed to accommodate the circumstances of the war reflect the notion that all 70 Withuis, supra note 1, at 109. 71 The term ‘wartime mayor’ became a Dutch expression for a Catch 22 situation: by remaining at his post, he gets his hands dirty; by leaving, he abandons his people. 72 See e.g. J. Cohen and H. Piersma (eds.), Moedige mensen: helden in oorlogstijd (Boom, 2014); see also the website of NIOD, on which, since 2007, staff members could name their ‘hero of the month’. More recently the site gives access to blogs about heroism and the ‘production’ of heroes (www.niod.knaw.nl/heldvandemaand). politically unsound individuals – and they alone – were perpetrators. The process therefore aimed at denying the politically unsound a place in society; the sanctions – life sentences, the death penalty, the ‘civil death’ of total confiscation of assets and denial of civil rights, lustration – were all intended to achieve just that. But in the absence of any connection to wartime realities, this concept could not, by definition, make good on its promises; neither could it do justice to the realities of the crimes and criminals of the occupation. Thus it was preconditioned to leave a legacy of divisiveness. Extraordinary justice has been criticised for this failure to promote a society conducive to an inclusive debate that could lead to reconciliation. 73 Given that it was founded on notions of exclusion that is hardly surprising. To expect the legal process to lead to reconciliation in such post-conflict situations, probably always asks too much of the criminal law, for it would be to ignore that every legal process is a function of the social and political context in which it operates 74 and, moreover, to conflate law and its application with justice. A court’s verdict is definite and authoritative; closure, not continued debate about what it establishes as legal truth, is its purpose. 75 Justice, like history with which it is closely intertwined, is an open-ended quest for historical truth and understanding. 76 In the context of conflict and transition, justice is a permanent struggle in different theatres of memory, confronting different truths of very complex, traumatic social and political events. It is a collective process and can only be achieved if all can recognise a collective version of the past, or at least the validity of different, contested memories. If the legal process of extraordinary justice failed, it is because it could not produce even the beginnings of a collective version of the past. That it did produce a divisive right- wrong dichotomy should not surprise: establishing ‘wrong’ as opposed to right is what criminal trials are about. But there was another inherent mechanism at work that is specific to the underlying ideology of Dutch post-war justice. The truth about the destruction of the Jewish people that emerged from the trials was a patchwork of collaboration and betrayal by individual perpetrators. To betray a Jew was a politically unpatriotic act that usually led to the death of the victim so that the maximum penalty was death (and indeed, death sentences were 73 Romijn, supa, note 7, at 20. 74 Which is, perhaps, a persuasive reason for not embarking on criminal trials immediately after the end of hostilities, and certainly not while they are still ongoing. 75 C.H, Brants and K. Klep, Transitional Justice, History Telling, Collective Memory and the Victim-Witness, 7 International Journal for Conflict and Violence (2013) 36-49, at 46. 76 J.C.H. Blom, Historische en strafrechtelijke ordening van de chaos, in: M. Spiering et al. (eds), De weerspannigheid van de feiten. Opstellen over geschiedenis, politiek, recht en literatuur aangeboden aan W.H. Robool (Verloren, 2000) 23-32, at 24-25. imposed and carried out), but it was no more nor less than any other act of betrayal that had cost lives. Parallel to the prevailing political and social discourse, victimhood was, literally, ‘neutralised’, so that the Holocaust as a phenomenon and the particular collective victimhood of the Jews (as opposed to the collective victimhood of the Dutch population as a whole) were not, and could not be, addressed as specific issues. Similarly, the identification of perpetrators as unpatriotic and politically unsound individuals buried the difficult moral question of the co-operation of almost the whole administration and the passive attitude of practically the whole population. That releases, pardons and reintegration schemes failed to bring reconciliation any closer despite the rhetoric of rebuilding the nation, is also logical. They were top-down policies that left the past behind and closed off divisions, while reconciliation is an ongoing social dialogue about precisely what it is that divides. That the path of justice in the Netherlands proved so rough is not simply a result of how its legal component operated. Criminal trials are but are small part of the process of justice itself and few now remember the contribution of extraordinary criminal justice at all. That criminal courts and tribunals sentenced tens of thousands in a series of trials lasting more than 6 years – no mean feat – is specialized, not general knowledge. Its contribution to a legacy of dichotomous public discourse, however, has proved lasting. The prevailing image of the reckoning, seen on television year after year around liberation day, is of men in old- fashioned raincoats and hats, hands in the air and a placard reading ‘traitor’ round their necks, manhandled through the streets by a couple of armed resistance men and a jeering mob; or of girls – moffenmeiden 77 – having their head roughly shaved amid the sunny festival-like atmosphere of newly liberated towns. It is the enduring imagery of right and wrong. Likewise, a lecture-series at the Resistance Museum in Amsterdam marking the 70 th anniversary of the end of the war bears the title ‘Heroes and Villains’. No Dutch person needs to be told what that means in the context of the war. 77 Saving the alliteration, best translated as ‘Boche-bitches’. work_hg3fd6adrzejtmedw4m5dhndxm ---- 269 EDU. INQ. Education Inquiry Vol. 1, No. 4, December 2010, pp.269–287 Social justice in education revisited1 Jan Nieuwenhuis* Abstract Social justice is a primary concern of politicians and human rights practitioners, but has lost much of its currency as it has been elevated through philosophical debates to the level of an idealised or “imagined social order” of modern state formations. This article is based on a conceptual analysis of social justice and the trajectory of philosophical discourse. It is argued that much of the social justice discourse ignores the specificity of the geo-historical and social contexts of developing coun- tries and it is premised that social justice in education should be based on a more holistic approach that takes these situational factors into account. Based on the conceptual analysis forwarded, it is postulated that social justice is not an external condition or system. If it were an external condi- tion or system, we could simply have learned social justice as we would have learned any other content-based subject. But social justice is an ideal – a vision that must become a way of life that permeates all aspects of being human. For this reason, it cannot be legislated or achieved through international conventions or declarations – albeit important instruments to promote social justice – social justice must come home in the hearts and minds of people and it must be lived. It requires that every citizen take responsibility to protect, advance and promote the values, principles and ideals of social justice, although for the marginalised and oppressed this is not enough. They need access to resources and opportunities for developing and exercising their capacities or capabilities for living a decent human life. Keywords: social justice, education, education policy, equality, conceptual analysis Introduction Maslow (1958: 15) observed that “I suppose it is tempting, if the only tool you have is a hammer, to treat everything as if it were a nail.” Looking at post-apartheid South Africa it seems that the hammer political decision-makers have found is policy. Democratic South Africa has developed a policy obsession whereby decision-makers want to cure all social ills with policies. The result is that we hammer and beat so- cial problems into a myriad of fragmented pieces and then develop a policy for each small segment. This is even more apparent within the field of education. There are four consequences of this. First, it kindles the flame of managerialism in government structures and spurs the forces of centralisation and control. Secondly, it results in organisations bullet-proofing themselves, thus creating a smoke-and-mirror environ- ment where organisations reflect the things they want government and the world to see, while hiding deeper lying concerns. Thirdly, by doing this, organisations achieve * Department of Education Management and Policy Studies, Faculty of Education, University of Pretoria E-mail: jan.nieuwenhuis@up.ac.za ©Authors. ISSN 2000-4508, pp.269–287 270 Jan Nieuwenhuis procedural or administrative compliance with the policy regime without achieving a much deeper level of substantive compliance (Nieuwenhuis, 2008). Finally, as a consequence of the fragmentation of social challenges and social justice concerns policymakers develop a kind of tunnel vision on social justice whereby they tend to focus on one specific social issue while losing sight of the bigger picture. Let me il- lustrate the consequences with two examples. In 2008, the world was shocked by an incident at the University of the Free State when a group of white students made a video in which a group of black cleaners from one of the hostels were humiliated and subjected to gross human injustice and degradation (Mail & Guardian, 2008). The students tried to justify their actions as a hoax, but it did reveal a much deeper attitude of racism and disrespect for the hu- man dignity and rights of fellow human beings. The university condemned the video outright and immediately claimed that the students’ actions were against university policy and that it was directly opposed to what the management of the former white university had tried to achieve with its transformational policies. A similar trend may be observed when looking at constitutional developments in Eastern European countries after the implosion of communism (1989-1991). Many of these Eastern European countries have reformed their constitutions in such a way as to bring human rights principles from the sphere of morals to the sphere of positive law (Gynther, 2009). For politicians and laymen of diverse ideological backgrounds, it is tempting to make use of rights-talk that, in a seemingly apolitical form, promises emancipation, equality and a better world to all intents and pur- poses. At grassroots level these promises are often experienced as empty and devoid of substance. In the end, much of what emerges from the fragmented discourse is what Mary Pichen has termed “grandiloquent incantation”: It obscures debate and provides no route for governments being held accountable for their actual practices (Pichen, 2001: 97). Two important observations must be made at this point: Gynther, (2009) reminds us of the distinction between formal equality and substantive equality. Writers on the topic agree that mere formal equality is not enough as equal application of a rule or law to all can have unequal results (Nieuwenhuis, 2005). The alternative, the substantive equality approach, can be divided into two distinct models: the difference model and the disadvantage model. The difference model has lost most of its support because of its normative indeterminacy. The disadvantage model defines equality in terms of disadvantage. The principle on which this model is based holds that “…if a person is a member of a constantly disadvantaged group and can show that a distinction based on the personal characteristics of the individual or the group and not imposed on others perpetuates or worsens that disadvantage, the distinction is discriminatory whether intentional or not” (Gynther, 2009: 2). Secondly, although human rights are claimed to be universal, what is actually at issue is a product of the Western liberal tradition, and even there merely one among many 271 Social justice in education revisited emancipatory vocabularies. As Kennedy (2004: 19) puts it: “Human rights encourage people to seek emancipation in the vocabularies of reason rather than faith, in public rather than private life, in law rather than politics, in politics rather than economics.” Against this background I embark on a conceptual analysis to revisit social jus- tice in education. In doing this I undertake to look at some of the formulations and conceptualisations of social justice and indicate why these formulations are deficient in a developing country context. Secondly, in using the conceptual analysis I argue that some of the commonly held assumptions about social justice are lacking in com- prehensiveness and that, as long as these are taken as a point of departure, we may never be able to achieve social justice in education in a developing country context. Research approach The research design utilised in this study is non-empirical in the classical sense of the word (cf. Mouton, 2001; McMillan and Schumacher, 1997), but rather qualitative and analytical (McMillan and Schumacher, 1997: 32). It is non-empirical as it relies on existing or secondary data of a textual nature and it is qualitative since its meth- odology is that of conceptual analyses. It is analytical because it relies on a reflexive analysis of various kinds of textual and other data. The research is also informed by the view of Neuman (1994: 384), namely that: By looking at historical events or diverse cultural contexts, a researcher can generate new concepts and broaden his or her perspectives. Concepts are less likely to be restricted to a historical time or to a single culture; they can be grounded in the experience of people living in specific cultural and historical contexts. It should also be noted that the nature and structure of concepts have been the focus of various strands of thought, most notably of analytic philosophy. Analysing concepts and statements represents the hub of activity in analytic philosophy and diverse views on analysis are generated within this philosophical tradition (see Beany, 1998). Simi- larly, diverse views exist about the nature of concepts which is sometimes described as “mental formulations of experience” (Chinn and Kramer, 1999: 78) or as “words describing mental images of phenomena” (Fawcett, 1999: 2). Rodgers (2000: 7-31) provides a useful overview of the philosophical debates about the nature of concepts and concludes that there is only a tentative answer to questions about the nature of concepts, although there is a consensus: … tha concepts are cognitive in nature and that they are comprised of attributes abstracted from reality, expressed in some form and utilized for some common purpose. Consequently, concepts are more than words or mental images alone. In addition, an emphasis on use alone is not sufficient to capture the complex nature of concepts (ibid: 30). Morse et al. (1997: 76) capture the purpose of concept analysis that forms the basis of this study, as follows: 272 Jan Nieuwenhuis (a) to identify gaps in …knowledge; (b) to determine the need to refine or clarify a concept … (c) to evaluate the adequacy of competing concepts in their relations to phenomena; (d) to examine the congruence between the definition of the concept and the way is has been opera- tionalized; or (e) to ascertain the fit between the definition of the concept and its …application. The above attempt at defining the nature of concepts is unavoidably tentative since considerable diversity exists around the matter. This diversity has research meth- odological implications that hinge on the nature of the problem to be researched; the philosophical orientation towards the nature of concepts; and the history of the concept (ibid: 28-29). In this article the concept of social justice is considered within the context of social, economic, political and cultural arrangements that have shaped and continue to shape its meanings within a developing country context. Formulations of social justice Formulations of the concept of social justice have a long history that includes the social contract theories of Locke, Rosseau, Kant, Hobbes and others. It is not my intention to offer an overview of these theories here, but to take the Rawlsian notion of “distributive justice” as my point of departure. Rawls (as quoted by Keet, 2006) argues that the “conception of social justice” is to be regarded as providing “...in the first instance a standard whereby the distributive aspects of the basic structure of society are to be assessed.” This standard should form the basis for “assigning rights and duties and defining the appropriate division of social advantages” (ibid: 234). For Rawls (1971) social justice provides a moral frame for modern democracy to come to full expression. It governs the conduct of people in relation to each other. Rawls (1958) further argues that not only does it bring out the idea that justice is a primitive moral notion in that it arises once the concept of morality is imposed on mutually self-interested agents similarly circumstanced, but it emphasises that, fundamental to justice, is the concept of fairness which relates to right dealing between persons who are co-operating with or competing against one another. The question of fairness arises when free persons, who have no authority over one another, are engaging in a joint activity and amongst themselves settling or acknowledging the rules which define it and which determine the respective shares in its benefits and burdens. Central to Rawls’ argument is the idea that justice is concerned with establishing the priority of that which is right over that which is good. While goodness can be determined in different kinds of ways, the principles of what is right and just place limitations on the individual’s ability to privilege his or her own best interests. He argues that a well-ordered society requires individuals with highly developed moral sensibilities. One may think of a public conception of social justice as constituting the fundamental charter of a well-ordered human association (Rawls, 1971:5). Rawls (1958) offers two principles of social justice: the principle of Equal Liberty claiming that each person is to be granted the greatest degree of liberty consistent with similar liberty for everyone, and, secondly, the Difference Principle, stating that 273 Social justice in education revisited practices that produce inequalities among individuals are allowable only if they work out to everyone’s advantage and the positions that come with greater reward are open to all. In essence then, Rawls puts forward the case for distributive justice. The notion of “distributive justice” is also supported by Robert Nozick (1996: 187), but Nozick offers an alternative in his entitlement conception of justice. For Nozick (1996), any distributive state arrived at from a just initial state by means of just transfers will itself be just. This has the result that one person might be justified in living in luxury while others around him are in dire poverty or even starving. He argues for a minimalist state intervention and for the “free operation of the market system” which must provide for the optimisation of opportunities for everyone. In searching for a theory of social justice in education, Brighouse (2002) argues that a theory on social justice in education is needed that has to inform us what rights people have, which efforts merit strong state protection, how rights should be distrib- uted and principles to manage trade-offs. He asserts that egalitarian liberalism is a normative theory of what ought to be – it is concerned with what principles should guide the design and reform of society. According to Brighouse (2002), egalitarian liberalism is rooted in the conviction that all individuals need a certain minimum of liberties (see Rawls) and that the state must make them accessible to all (see No- zick). Brighouse (2002) proposes two principles that should guide social justice in education: fair equality of opportunity and equality of condition. Equal opportunity concentrates on treating all people equally and providing people with equal rights. Treating everyone the same does not necessarily mean fairness of treatment. Equal- ity of opportunity is restricted by the family background and circumstances that put children at a disadvantage. The provision of equality of opportunity must be combined with social justice principles to provide substantive equality to marginalised groups (see Nieuwenhuis, 2005). Social justice provides equitable outcomes to marginalised groups by recognising past disadvantage and existence of structural barriers embed- ded in the social, economic and political system that perpetuate systemic discrimina- tion. Social justice recognises that there are situations where the application of the same rules to unequal groups can generate unequal results. Social justice provides a framework to assess the impact of policies and practices. Following the line of reasoning put forward by Rawls, Brighouse (2002) asserts that to achieve social justice in education, two principles are needed: personal autonomy and educational equality. Principle of autonomy states that each child should have the opportunity to become an autonomous person. He should be able to step back and reflect on the self and educators have the duty to facilitate the process where people can become autonomous. Educational equality is based on the idea that the state must guarantee a set of liberties implying that each child shall have right to equally good education. Equality then means more resources to those with less (e.g. the blind) to ensure the same quality. The quality principle therefore proposes that those with similar levels of ability and willing to exert the similar level of effort should faced 274 Jan Nieuwenhuis similar prospects regardless of background and, secondly, those with lower levels of ability should receive additional resources than those with more abilities. The liberal stance taken by authors like Rawls, Nozick and Brighouse on social justice has been critiqued from various sides. Pitt (1998), for example, argues that social justice in education in “new times” is aligned to an ideology of liberal democracy resulting in the emergence of a hyper individualism. This has resulted in the language of economics dominating the social justice and educational debate (see Michael Ap- ple, 1995). In such a situation the social whole, social identity and social cohesion are marginalised. This produces a curriculum which focuses on the education of the individual for economic imperatives. For Pitt (1998) social justice policies act as a political lever to legitimate economic restructuring – they are policies designed to carry disparate groups forward and together, on a common wave of economic reform. Social justice policies are therefore paraded as being “good” for all of society and, in this sense, they are used to “sell” economic reform. Against the backdrop of economic rationalism and liberal democratic ideals, there emerges a language geared to the production of an economically viable self-image, identity, esteem and confidence. As a result, the sense of identity as “social” disappears from view. It erodes the individual’s responsibility towards the group. MacIntyre (1992) also rebukes the liberal notions of justice of Rawls and Nozick, claiming that it is premised on an impossible consensus on a range of principles of moral origin and that the Aristotelian and Lockean notion of “justice as a virtue”, which supports the notions of Rawls and Nozick, must be abandoned (MacIntyre, 1992: 199). MacIntyre (ibid: 200-202) further admonishes the centrality of the values of the market place which have displaced the tradition of virtues and insists on the impossibility of genuine moral consensus. This, in turn, makes the social justice no- tions of Rawls and Nozick logically indefensible. Taylor (1990) also takes issue with Rawls’ ideas by showing how much a traditional Rawlsian position frees the citizen from the responsibility to act. The position taken by Taylor is that citizenship requires that the individual commits him or herself to a moral position. Practical reasoning or a deontological approach (i.e. the moral imperative to act in terms of what is morally right) is central to the active citizen. Gewirtz and Cribb (2002) also reject the liberal view of social justice. They argue for the plurality of the notion of social justice which extends beyond “distributive justice”. Such a plural notion includes “distributive justice”, “cultural justice” and “as- sociational justice” and these notions exhibit varied meanings on a conceptual plane. Griffiths (2003: 7) similarly talks of the plural “theories of social justice” in education and views “social justice” as “dynamic, as a verb” with the emphasis on “uncertainty, fallibility and risky judgements” in order for us to be all humanly different (ibid: 142). A different position taken is that of Giddens. Giddens (1994) approaches social justice from a radical politics perspective and suggests a framework which draws on philo- sophic conservatism. It is a framework which connects autonomy with personal and 275 Social justice in education revisited collective responsibility. Giddens (1994: 10) labels such a philosophical framework as “a philosophy of protection, conservation and solidarity”. It is a framework which also preserves some of the core values which have been associated with socialism (Gid- dens 1994). There are six key points in the framework proposed by Giddens (1994): • repairing damaged solidarities by reconciling autonomy and interdependence; • recognising the importance of the discussion of ethics, i.e. “life politics”; • allowing individuals and groups to make things happen, a “generative politics”; • creating a democracy where issues are debated openly by the public; • developing a welfare state which is empowering rather than merely dispens- ing; and • confronting the role violence plays at all levels of human affairs. The intention of Giddens (1991) is to build on the gains resulting from the emergence of human dignity, such as human rights, while at the same time curbing the excesses of individual agency suggested by Rawls. A related line of thinking is found in the work of Nussbaum and Sen which offer a conceptually rich notion of “capabilities” as a normative framework for promoting human well-being and social justice in de- velopment debates (also see Unterhalter, 2003, Robeyns, 2006). Martha Nussbaum (2000) and Amartya Sen (1999) approach social justice from a different angle by proposing a universal set of capabilities that, together, mark what we as human should be able to be and do in order to meet at least the threshold for living in a fully human way. The capability approach developed by Sen and Nussbaum through dialogue and disagreement for over nearly 20 years (Sen, 1981, 1992, 1999; Nussbaum and Sen, 1993; Nussbaum and Glover, 1995; Nussbaum, 2000) proposes that each of the capabilities is crucial and each is qualitatively different from the rest, yet they are also related to each other, in a variety of complex ways. Sen (1999) argues that capabilities – i.e. well being achievement, well being freedom, agency achievement and agency freedom – should be taken as the way to assess any policy or practice. According to Sen, in evaluating social welfare, including education, capabili- ties should be equalised, although other aspects of social identities will necessarily be different. Nussbaum (2000) has linked the notion of capabilities not only to an evaluative process with regard to thinking of justice in a range of different settings, but also to a normative exploration of humanness. Nussbaum (2000) proposes a list of ten central human capabilities, which she regards as the core entitlements for human flourishing and living life with dignity. Nussbaum (2000) makes the important point that governments cannot be expected to deliver all the capabilities, nonetheless “in the political arena” certain human capabilities exert “a moral claim that they should be developed” (ibid: 83). Where resources are sufficient, failure by government to develop central capabilities becomes a social justice problem. The capabilities proposed by Nussbaum (2000: 78-80) are: 276 Jan Nieuwenhuis • Life – living a fully human life of a normal span; • Bodily health – being adequately nourished, and with shelter; • Bodily integrity – including freedom of movement, security from various kinds of assault, and opportunities for sexual expression and reproductive choice; • Using one’s senses – imagination and thought, with freedom of expression and conscience; • Emotions – in freedom of attachment and association; • Practical reason – including forming a conception of the good and a life plan, with liberty of conscience; • Affiliation with others in forms of social interaction like friendship and work, protected against discrimination; • Relating to other species; • Play; and • Control over one’s environment, both political and material. Sen and Nussbaum’s work on the capability approach has largely focused on clarify- ing concepts, rather than on applying them in specific institutional contexts. Their formulation of the capability approach has emerged out of debates in liberal political theory and rooted in ethical individualism. Conceptualising social justice in a developing country context The overview presented above reveals a situation where the social justice discourse has been colonised by the dominant Western philosophical and political approach and has largely became a symbol used to legitimate Eurocentric material practices and to consolidate their dominance in world forums. The policies and practices of the dominant social group led to social justice being defined according to economic gain, while marginal themes focus more on the development of social cohesion and a sense of community. In this regard, Cox (as quoted by Pitt, 1998) takes issue with the idea of the citizen as a competitive individual. She urges for a conception of the citizen which goes beyond economic frameworks and recognises the location of human beings within what she refers to as social networks and the social, as opposed to the economic, capital that animates their relationships with one another. Much of what I have presented thus far is based on the conceptualisation of an ideal- ised or “imagined social order” of modern state formations. Because they are idealised and abstracted from context, they bear distinctive signs of their Western modernist legacy (Christie, 2009). Christie (2009) notes that the realities of educational provision in many of the countries of the world – even relatively rich Western countries – do not always match these ideals. Though these ideals provide a hegemonic norm for what education across the world should look like, they are certainly out of the reach 277 Social justice in education revisited of most of the world’s children, as numerous EFA reports show (Unterhalter, 2005). Although the principles and frameworks developed may offer guidelines in terms of the development of legislation and policies, they remain barren abstractions that cannot prevail over socio-economic and political contexts which fundamentally shape what form rights and therefore social justice take in practice. In this regard, Balibar (2006: 25) asserts that: “different geo-histories engender profoundly heterogeneous points of view on the same questions of principle”. In contrast to wealthier countries, poor countries may simply be unable to afford what international conventions and treaties require them to do, more especially in terms of ideals such as “Education for All”. Developing countries may not have the economic resources or political will to provide the type of quality education for all envisaged by the international agenda written in the conference rooms of Paris or Washington. But even if developing countries had the resources and political will, cultural beliefs and practices may work against the right to equality or protection against discrimination (Christie, 2009). In addition, when discussing the markets in education Ball (1993) claims that in the ideal environment every parent is free to make a choice on a school he/she wants to educate his/her children, but the choice is actually never “open” to everybody. In fact, parents who live in a rural area with only one poorly resourced school and poorly trained teachers available to their children are constrained in their school choice and this may result in no choice at all. Their children will never receive the type of equal quality education advocated. In practical terms, this implies that the right to education for all is limited by the socio-economic realities operating at grassroots level. I would thus like to argue that we need to look at social justice in education not from an idealised theoretical angle, but that we need to depart from the social realities of the situation within which social justice must be achieved. Approaching the concept of social justice as a geo-historical situational bound construction opens it up to con- tinual reconstruction, without foreclosing future forms (Christie, 2009). From a geo- historically perspective, I accept that social-justice is embedded in a struggle for social change, particularly struggles against domination and oppression of varying kinds. In this regard, Henkin (1989) usefully points out that human rights as we currently know them are not about philosophical notions of justice, democracy or “the good society”. Rather, they are about claims which individuals may legitimately make upon their socie- ties for certain defined freedoms and benefits. In similar vein, Mandela (1994) stated: “Our single most important challenge is therefore to help establish a social order in which the freedom of the individual will truly mean the freedom of the individual…. Our definition of the freedom of the individual must be instructed by the fundamental objective to restore the human dignity of each and every South African.” Looking then at social justice and education in South Africa Fiske and Ladd (2004: 233) suggest that while South Africa has made good progress in some respects, “(a) long other dimensions, however, equity has remained elusive for reasons largely related to the country’s historical legacy and the pressures it faced as a result of the 278 Jan Nieuwenhuis new global economic environment.” Many of the freedoms gained after 1994 have only remained available to black families in urban areas with the ability to pay high school fees, transportation and other costs. The majority of black families continue to live in townships and rural areas that were part of the apartheid system and most attend schools that continue to be poorly provided for and have poorly trained teach- ers (Fiske and Ladd: 2004). Du Toit (2004) identifies four failures of post-apartheid SA. Firstly, there is little indication that the impact of HIV/AIDS can be moderated, let alone turned around, in the immediate future. An estimated 5.6 million South Africans were HIV positive in 2008, the largest number of any country in the world (Nicolay, 2008). Secondly, violent crime remains at a very high level. In the first ten years of democracy, close to a quarter of a million South Africans (about 230,000) have been murdered. More than 300,000 have survived such attacks and are recorded as victims of attempted murder. Another million or so have become victims of robbery with aggravating circumstances (Du Toit, 2004). Thirdly, poverty remains pervasive. Despite the very successful extension of service delivery, especially those that relate to hard services, by 2005 there were still more than 22 million South Africans (about 48% of the total population) living in poverty (Appel, 2008). Finally, in the midst of this problem of development lies the issue of unemployment inextricably linked to poverty and inequality, and also to crime and HIV/AIDS. Up to this point in time, the problem of unemployment has not abated. In 2009, 12.89 million people were unemployed (Mail & Guardian, 2009). Every one of the above failures of governance impacts ad- versely on human dignity and the eluding ideal of social justice. Section 9 (1) of the South African Constitution states that: “Everyone is equal before the law and has the right to equal protection and benefit of the law”. This is immediately followed by the proviso (Section 9(2)) that “Equality includes the full and equal enjoyment of all rights and freedoms” (Republic of South Africa, 1996). This promise is vacuous in achieving social justice if the failures are not addressed. In the light of these failures we need to look at the capacity of the state to address these failures. Omano (2007) describes the state capacity as the ability of the state to act authoritatively to transform the structural basis of the economy to achieve economic growth, reduce poverty and income and wealth inequalities. Inclusiveness and social justice are central to this conception. Although a number of gains could be claimed in terms of a reduction in both absolute income poverty, which is the income of poor people, and in relative income poverty, social development through social grants, housing, water and sanitation, Netshitenzhe (in Appel, 2008) noted that many studies, including the Income Expenditure Survey by Statistics South Africa, have found a widening inequality gap in the country. Omano (2007) identifies a number of aspects on which the state lacks capacity to come to terms with these failures. In part, the lack of capacity may be because the democratic state lacks the resources, human and material, to meet the myriad of needs. 279 Social justice in education revisited Looking at social justice in education then would require that we do not simply treat it as a theoretical abstract exercise, but that we take the social context and capacity of the state into consideration. Young (1990; 2000) asserts that we need to be concerned, not only with just procedures, but also with just outcomes. For her, a theory of social justice that recognises human agency, and so gives primacy to doing rather than to having, must start with an account of social injustice (Young, 1990). By prioritising doing over having she casts doubt on distributive accounts and shifts attention to the role of just procedures as a way of achieving more just outcomes under initial condi- tions of structural inequality in which the social positions of some people constrain their freedom and well-being and, may I add, also their capabilities. Where race and class produce unequal effects, as in South Africa, we can hardly claim that children have equal rights to education. But even where race and class differentials do not exist at community level other socio-economic factors, such as poverty and unemployment or violence and child abuse or child neglect, will work against achieving the type of social justice that we may propagate at a theoretical level. I would like to argue that you cannot develop a theory of social justice from a predominantly first-world context where the realities of poverty, unemployment and oppression are ignored. The context within which social justice must be acted on cannot be negated in the development of an idealistic notion of what social justice should achieve. Here again, I think it is important to link up with the work of Young (2000) when she states that ideally, social justice requires the establishment of institutional and other structural conditions for promoting self-determination and self-development of all members of society. These two ideals of social justice are pitted against the two general conditions of injustice, namely, domination and oppression, which are the main impediments to the achievement of genuine agency. Young (2000) describe op- pression in terms of five “faces”2 that inhibit people’s capacity for self development. Marginalisation and powerlessness, the faces most pertinent in developing country contexts, are structural forms of oppression that act against meaningful social justice. Marginalisation occurs when a whole category of people is excluded from meaningful participation in social life and is thus potentially vulnerable to deprivation and even extermination. The ongoing poor service delivery uprisings in many parts of South Africa are indicative of the extent to which marginalisation and oppression continue to plaque poorer communities in our society. Further, genuine inclusion has to overcome external and internal exclusion. Exter- nally excluded groups remain outside of both the distributive domains for public goods and the arenas of public deliberation. External exclusion can be variously imposed; for example, through policies like affirmative action or social practices such as the domestic confinement of women to the home and menial work. Internal exclusion can be much more insidious. Under the pretence of inclusion, previously excluded groups may be brought into a public deliberative domain but remain on the margins of deliberation (Young, 2000). Learners previously excluded from white educational 280 Jan Nieuwenhuis institutions in South Africa may thus be brought into institutions of learning, but their needs, aspirations and participation remain on the periphery. The implication of the aforementioned is that strategies are required to ensure substantive inclusion and the elimination of marginalisation and oppression. Miller (1999) proposes three substantive principles of social justice – need, desert and equality – each linked to a mode of human relationship, regarded as an ideal type. In a relationship of “solidaristic community” the principle of justice is distributed according to need. Each member of such a community (a family or a religious group, for example) is obliged to assist in meeting others’ needs, in proportion to their ability to do so. As a principle of justice, needs must be able to function in circumstances of relative scarcity where not every need can be met and where needs will compete with other demands. In a relationship of instrumental association, dessert is the principle for just distribution. Typically, Miller (1999) argues, the purposes of an organisation set the criteria for dessert, and justice is done when each member of the organisation receives a reward equivalent to the contribution s/he makes. Equality is the primary principle of just distribution in a relationship of citizenship. Equality is a principle of social justice only in limited circumstances (Miller, 1999). Although justice and distributive equality share a logical grammar, justice does not always require equal distribution. What is more, equality is not a singular concept. Unlike distributive equality, social equality (or equality of status) is not directly connected to justice for, while it identifies an ideal, it does not specify any distribution of rights or resources (Miller, 1999). Given this critique and analysis of social justice and bringing to bear the realities of social justice within a developing country context, we can now try and determine the space of social justice from a more holistic perspective. Social justice seen from a holistic perspective I now venture to conceptualise social justice from a more holistic perspective by tak- ing the geo-historical and socio-political context as a point of departure. The space of social justice within such a complex configuration is graphically illustrated in Figure 1. The basic notion is that social justice must be impressed within a force field of interacting push and pull forces as well as inhibitors. The push/pull forces consist of the historicity of the space wherein social justice is sought (the family, school, com- munity, state etc.); the social demands, expectations and agendas that actively promote a more just dispensation within the context; international trends and discourses (e.g. globalisation, education for all, marketisation of education etc.); and the dynamics of technological advances and economic imperatives for development and job creation. The very same push/pull forces can, however, also act as inhibitors of change (see the lightning bolts in the arrows in Figure 1). If we were to superimpose this conceptualisation on education we see a similar dynamic process in operation. In a developing country context, like South Africa, the 281 Social justice in education revisited social justice agenda at the level of the state is co-determined by the ideological as- sumptions of the ruling party, the policies that flows from it. As the state endeavours to create policy frameworks to address all the concerns and to satisfy its constituency, it may create elaborate frameworks that operate more as political symbolism (Jansen, 2001) rather than genuine attempts to come to terms with the real concerns. This is so as policies are moderated by the co-determinants of scarcity of resources and op- portunity cost. There are two consequences of this. First, in prioritising a particular concern over others, the state will allocate funds to that concern (e.g. creating elabo- rative administrative structures or focusing on a particular sector of the education system, like basic education), thus diverting funds away from other social justice concerns that could have been served. Second, to satisfy its constituency base it may adopt a specific political stance and develop particular policies on a social issue without allocating funds or political will to the concern (e.g. the inclusion of Grade R as part of compulsory education without allocating funds to it to make it part of the formal system of education) which then results in the policies taking on a symbolic nature. The gap between policy and praxis is thus widened. The inability of the state to provide effective service delivery in townships and informal settlements in South Africa over the past number of years and the resultant ongoing violence and demonstrations is a case in point. Only those social justice issues that are actively pursued feature on the state agenda and are thus controlled and subjected to increased managerialism. Figure 1. The space of social justice in education: a holistic perspective Social demands expectations agendas Historicity Socio-political Cultural Morals Ideology Religion State Ideology Policy Scarcity Opportunity cost School Tradition Convention Culture Climate Curriculum Economic development Aspirations Innovation Technological Community ideals International discourse conventions declarations instruments Push forces Push forces Pull forces Pull forces 282 Jan Nieuwenhuis At the school level where policies must be implemented, the same push and pull forces are in operation but, admittedly, international forces may have less of an impact on the local level. The other factors that have helped shaped the school’s tradition, conven- tions, culture, climate and curriculum in operation (including the hidden curriculum) may operate as strong inhibitors to change. The result of this is that policies handed down from the state are dealt with in a way that will ensure statutory or administra- tive compliance, without addressing the deeper underlying assumptions, values and beliefs of the school. Any system committed to creating greater social justice in education will not suc- ceed unless it addresses social justice in a more comprehensive or holistic manner. This, in turn, implies that any state that is committed to social justice in education must come to terms with the following challenges in conceptualising its strategies aimed at promoting and advancing social justice in education: 1. Accept that social justice is not an external condition or system. If it were an external condition or system, we could simply have learned social justice as we would have learned any other content-based subject in schools. Social justice is an ideal – a vision – that should be reinvented and reinvigorated by each generation (Knight, 2001) so that it becomes a way of life that perme- ates all aspects of our lives. It requires that every citizen take responsibility to protect, advance and promote the values, principles and ideals of social justice. South African history bears witness to the long struggle to realise the ideal of social justice. Whether we succeed in protecting and advancing social justice will depend on the will and ability of all the citizens of the country to work towards shaping social justice in all spheres of life. 2. Realise the importance of creating personal agency that is supportive of social justice. The statement of Rawls (1971) that a well-ordered society requires individuals with highly developed moral sensibilities is important in this regard. The question is: Is justice without morality possible? I am convinced that social justice cannot be served in any shape or form in a self-interested and immoral society. It is not about pointing fingers or playing the blame game where we accuse others of how immoral and corrupt they are. It starts with taking responsibility for the self and to live the values that will promote social justice. Social justice remains an empty ideal unless we can infuse it with meaning by basing justice on certain moral principles and empower people to take personal responsibility for doing and extending justice to oth- ers. This is aligned with the principle that each member of such a community (a family or a religious group, for example) is obliged to assist in meeting others’ needs, in proportion to their ability to do so (Miller, 1999). The state should thus take human agency seriously and enable the self-development and self-determination of all citizens (Pendlebury & Enslin, 2004). 283 Social justice in education revisited 3. Justice must be achieved amidst scarcity. As a principle of justice, need must be able to function in circumstances of relative scarcity, where not every need can be met and where needs will compete with other demands (Miller, 1999). In a developing country context the state will be required to move more and more in the direction of a welfare state or what Nussbaum (2000) calls ensuring bodily health, that is adequately nourished, and with shelter. In these conditions the welfare state must be empowering rather than merely dispensing (Giddens, 1991). In terms of education, it implies that the state provides opportunities and support for all children to exercise the range of functions necessary for developing their mature adult capabilities (Pendlebury & Enslin, 2004). 4. Accept the geo-historical history of the struggle as something that must be reconciled with attempts to create social justice. This implies that the state must work with communities to repair damaged solidarities by reconciling autonomy and interdependence (Giddens, 1991). It also implies the elimina- tion of structural forms of oppression that restrict people’s access to resources and opportunities for developing and exercising their capacities or capabili- ties for living a decent human life (Young, 2002). In doing this, care must be taken not to create new forms of exclusion that will create new forms of social injustice. Similarly, it must ensure fairness in terms of rewards. You cannot reward state officials for failing to deliver the social services intended to create a just society. Justice is done when each member of an organisation receives a reward equivalent to the contribution s/he makes (Rawls, 1971; Miller, 1999). This also applies to education. You cannot reward a child if no contribution has been forthcoming, and you cannot reward educators for not performing at the level required from them. For example, you cannot promote a child to the next grade automatically if s/he has not participated in the educational process on an equal basis with others. Conclusion Brighouse (2002) asserts that, until recently, no theory of justice in education ex- isted and that we cannot simply read a theory off from Rawls, Young, Giddens or any other author. In this article I have critically reviewed a number of theories that could inform such a theory of social justice in education. I have argued that social justice is an ideal – a vision that must become a way of life that permeates all aspects of being human. For this, reason it cannot be legislated or achieved through interna- tional conventions or declarations – albeit important instruments to promote social justice – social justice must be lived. It requires that every citizen take responsibility to protect, advance and promote the values, principles and ideals of social justice, although for the marginalised and oppressed this is not enough. They need access to 284 Jan Nieuwenhuis resources and opportunities for developing and exercising their capacities or capabili- ties for living a decent human life. The road to achieving this is, however, obstructed by the geo-historical and scarcity challenges faced by developing countries. These challenges and their negative impact on achieving social justice in education must be addressed. As long as these conditions exist there cannot be social justice. It is a journey that all developing countries and their people must embark on. In the Long Walk to Freedom Nelson Mandela (1994:751) said: Some say that (the liberation of the oppressed and the oppressor) has now been achieved. But I know that that is not the case. The truth is that we are not yet free: we have merely achieved the freedom to be free, the right not to be oppressed. We have not taken the final step of our journey, but the first step on a longer and even more difficult road. For to be free is not merely to cast off one’s chains, but to live in a way that respects and enhances the freedom of others. Jan Nieuwenhuis is an Associate Professor in the Department of Education Management and Policy Studies of the Faculty of Education at the University of Pretoria, South Africa. He has been involved with educational research since 1979. He has published more than 40 technical research reports, two academic books, contributed eight chapters to academic books, published twelve articles in academic journals as an author or co-author and delivered numerous papers at national and inter- national conferences. His research interest is in the field of values and human rights in education. 285 Social justice in education revisited References Appel, Michael. (2008) Poverty in South Africa ‘is declining’ 2 October 2008 http://www.southa- frica.info/about/social/poverty-021008.htm Apple, M.W. (1995) Education and power. (2ND Edition). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Balibar, E. (2006) Constructions and deconstructions of the universal. Critical Horizons 7 (1): 21–43. Ball, S.J. (1993) Education Markets, Choice and Social Class: the market as a class strategy in the UK and the USA. British Journal of Sociology of Education 14 (1): 3-19. Beaney, M. (1998) ‘What is Analytic Philosophy? Recent Work on the History of Analytic Philoso- phy’, British Journal for the History of Philosophy 6: 463-72. Brighouse, H. (2002) Egalitarian liberalism and justice in education. Political Quarterly, 2002: 181-190. Chinn, P. L., & Kramer, M.K. (1999) Theory and nursing: Integrated knowledge development (5th Edition). St. Louis, MO: Mosby. Christie, P. (2010) The complexity of human rights in global times: The case of the right to educa- tion. International Journal of Educational Development 30: 3-11. Du Toit, P. (2004) Affirmative Action and the Politics of Transformation: A Survey of Public Opinion. A study commissioned by the F W de Klerk Foundation August 2004. Fawcett, J. (1999) The relationship of theory and research (3rd Edition). Philadelphia: F.A. Davis. Fiske, E.B., Ladd, H.F. (2004) Elusive Equity: Education Reform in post-Apartheid South Africa. Brookings Institute/HSRC Press, Washington, DC/Cape Town. Gewirtz, S. & Cribb, A. (2009) Towards a contextualized analysis of social justice in education Educational Philosophy and Theory 1, (1): 69-81. Giddens, A. (1991) Modernity and Self-Identity, Stanford: Stanford University Press. Giddens, A. (1994) Beyond Left and Right: The Future of Radical Politics. Cambridge: Polity. Griffiths, M. (2003) Action for Social Justice in Education. London: Open University Press. Gynther, P. (2009) Basic Skills Provision for the Have-Not’s: A Rights Hoax? Re-Examining Inter- national Standards on the Right to Education. Date of submission: July 22, 2009. Henkin, L. (1989) Universality of the concept of human rights. The Annals of the American Acad- emy 506: 10–16. Jansen, J.D. (2001) Rethinking Education Policy in South Africa: Symbols of change, Signals of Conflict. In Kraak, A & Young, M (eds.). Education in Retrospect: Policy and Implementation Since 1990. Pretoria: HSRC. Keet, A. (2006) Concept Analysis of Human Rights Education. Unpublished PhD Thesis. Univer- sity of Pretoria. South Africa. Kennedy, D. (2004) The Dark Sides of Virtue. Princeton: Princeton University Press Knight, T. (2001) Longitudinal development of educational theory: democracy and the classroom. Journal of Education Policy, 16(3): 249-263. MacIntyre, A. (1985) After Virtue. (2nd Edition), Duckworth, London. Mail and Guardian. (2008). Racist video surfaces at the University of the Free State. 26 February 2008. Mail & Guardian (2009) SA unemployment rate increases. 29 October 2009. Mandela, N. (1994) The long walk to freedom. London: Brown and Company. Mandela, Nelson. (1994) State of the Nation Address, Cape Town: Parliament, 24 May 1994. Maslow, A. H. (1966) The Psychology of Science: A Reconnaissance. New York: Harper & Row. 286 Jan Nieuwenhuis McMillan, J. H., & Schumacher, S. S. (1997) Research in Education: A Conceptual Introduction. New York: Longman. Miller, D. (1999) Principles of social justice. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. Morse, J. M., Hupcey, J. E., Mitcham, C., & Lenz, E. R. (1997) Choosing a strategy for concept analysis in nursing research: Moving beyond Wilson. In Gift, A. G. (ed.), Clarifying concepts in nursing research. New York: Springer: 73-96. Mouton, J. (2001) How to succeed in your Master’s and Doctoral Studies, A South African Guide and Resource Book. Pretoria: Van Schaik Publishers. Neuman, W.L. (1994) Social Research Methods: Qualitative and Quantitative Approaches (2nd Edition). Boston: Allyn and Bacon. Nicolay, Nathea, (2008) AIDS and Demographic model. Metropolitan www.actuarialsociety.org. za (Accessed on 12 December 2009). Nieuwenhuis, FJ. (2005) From equality of opportunity to equality of treatment as a value-based concern in education. In: Russo, C., Beckman JL and Jansen, J.D. (eds.) Equal Educational Opportunities: Comparative Perspectives in Education. Pretoria: Van Schaik. Nieuwenhuis, F.J. (2008) Organisational change: From adjusting the clock to morphogenesis. In: Weber,E (ed.) Educational Change in South Africa. Rotterdam: Sense Publishers. Nozick, R. (1996) Distributive Justice. In Cahn, S. et al (eds.) Reason at Work. Forth Worth: Har- court Brace. Nussbaum, M.C. (2000) Women and development. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Nussbaum, M., Glover, J. (eds.) (1995) Women, Culture and Development. Clarendon Press, Ox- ford. Nussbaum, M., Sen, A. (eds.) (1993) The Quality of Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press 303–323. Omano, E. (2007) Affirmative Action and State Capacity in a Democratic South Africa. Johan- nesburg: Centre for Policy Studies. Pendlebury, S. and Enslin, P. (2004) Social justice and inclusion in education and politics: the South African case Journal of Education, 34: 31-43. Pichen, M., (2001) Ethical foreign policies and human rights: dilemmas for non government or- ganisations. In: Smith, K.E., Light, M. (eds.) Ethics and Foreign Policy. Cambridge: Cam- bridge University Press, 93–111. Pitt, Jane. (1998) Social justice in education in ’new times.’ Paper delivered Wednesday, 2 Decem- ber 1998. Australian Association for Research in Education Annual Conference. 29 November - 3 December 1998. Rawls, J. (1958) Justice as fairness. Philosophical Review, 67: 164-194. Rawls, J. (1971) A Theory of Justice. Cambridge, Mass: The Belknap Press. Republic of South Africa. (1996) The Constitution of the Republic of South Africa, 1996. (Act No. 108 of 1996). Cape Town: Government Printer. Robeyns, I. (2003) Sen’s capability approach and gender inequality: selecting relevant capabili- ties. Feminist Economics online at http://www.ingridrobeyns.nl/Downloads/FE_Sen_GI.pdf (Accessed 15 June 2005). Rodgers, B. L. (2000) Philosophical foundation of concept development. In B. L. Rodgers & K. A. Knafl (eds.), Concept development in nursing: Foundation, techniques and application. London: Saunders: 7-37. Sen, A., (1981) Poverty and Famines. Clarendon Press, Oxford. Sen, A., (1992) Inequality Re-examined. Clarendon Press, Oxford. 287 Social justice in education revisited Sen, A., (1999) Development as Freedom. Oxford University Press, Oxford. Taylor, C. (1990) Sources of the Self. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Unterhalter, E. (2005) Global inequality, capabilities, social justice: The millennium development goal for gender equality in education. International Journal of Educational Development 25: 111–122. Young, I. M. (1990) Justice and the Politics of Difference. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton Uni- versity Press. Young, I. M. (2000) Inclusion and democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Endnotes 1 This article is based on a paper presented at the Örebro-Unisa International Conference 2010, South Africa (1-3 February 2010). 2 The five faces of oppression are exploitation, marginalisation, powerlessness, cultural imperial- ism and violence. work_hg4upa25x5ggjpsuh2wmuft4cm ---- Crime, Justice and Indigenous Peoples: the ‘New Justice’ and ‘Settler’ States Crime, Justice and Indigenous Peoples In Broadhurst, R.G. 1999, ‘Crime, Justice and Indigenous Peoples: The ‘New Justice’ and Settler States’, Australian and New Zealand Journal of Criminology, Vol. 32:105-108. Copyright 1999 Australian Academic Press Introduction The articles in this issue draw on cross-national comparisons of indigenous crime and justice in three ‘settler societies’, Australia, Canada and New Zealand. These kindred states share a common imperial history but their geo-political, cultural and historical trajectories are sufficiently different to reveal the underlying character of neo-colonial indigenous-state relations. Despite differences in indigenous culture, the timing of contact, the ‘civilizing’ or assimilationist mechanisms employed and constitutional form all states share an over-reliance on penal measures as a means of regulating indigenous-state relations. Yet considerable variations in the penal experience of Aborigines are observed so that differences are often greater amongst them than between Aborigines and non-Aborigines. These anomalies in indigenous criminalization are for Tyler (this issue) not only a product of anomie but reflect variations in economic dependency, cultural resilience, ethnic fluidity and 'identity' arising from the encounter with the post-colonial state. Given the economy of imprisonment as a means of regulating the disorder represented by the conflicts and strains of Aboriginal engagement with modernity, its deployment has been efficient in managing race conflict and cross-cultural inequalities. However, the extent to which the state can resort to policing institutions to manage the on-going encounter with indigenous people, is now subject to a pervasive (global) discourse on human rights. In 'liberal' neo-colonial states efforts to accomplish domestic de-colonization and incorporate Aborigines into the economy must accord with modern sensibilities about self-determination and 'difference'. However, ‘self-determination’ has proven difficult to define in practice, and “(I)t has been easier to say that ‘self-determination’ is not ‘assimilation’ than to say what it is” (Rowse 1998:205). Nevertheless, the state seeks consensual means for regulating the indigenous domain and has acquired new ideologies and orientations that accommodate cultural difference. Co-opted customary forms of dispute resolution, equated with self-determination, animated restorative or ‘new’ justice approaches in indigenous communities. Although restorative justice had emerged in a wider response to the percieved crisis in the control of juvenile delinquents it draw inspiration from the colonized (for example, native American ‘sentencing circles’ and Maori ‘family group conferences’) but are appropriations redolent of Orientalism (Blagg 1997). The notion of restorative justice relies on a re-imagined community where shaming is meaningful and a less costly means to control delinquency. As Tauri (this issue) has noted the cherished post-war liberal goal of assimilation realised by formal legal and political equality [glossed by incorporation of indigenous cultural symbols] for indigenous people as Australian, Canadian or New Zealand citizens has not lost its cogency. The privileging of formal legal rights over cultural, social and economic rights through notions of citizenship operates to confine ‘self- determination’ to choice within the framework of given forms of governmentality. Self determination, when realized as restorative justice may serve to limit indigenous autonomy. Thus contemporary penal practices that incorporate alternatives to incarceration such as restorative justice or ‘New Justice’ are, as LaPriarie (this issue) argues, a potent means of accommodating the enduring differences between the settlers and the indigenous inhabitants. The ‘New Justice’ permits problems of difference to be mediated at the local level without compromising the integrity of the state or the duties of citizenship. Yet La Priairie questions whether this elaboration (“doing justice differently”) amounts to little more than “responsibilization without resources”. Warfhuht, Palys and Boyce (this issue) in their account of one such programme in British Columbia, note an ever present risk to programme effectiveness was dependence on state support. Drawing on the inspiration of the Canim Lake people’s Family Violence Programme they stress processes that involve a self-consciously re-imagined sense of community that interrupted dependency created by assimilation. By 'owning the problem' communities address otherwise intractable problems of family violence and sexual abuse by evoking traditional healing. The process begins with self-help, listening and the withdrawal of state agencies from a central to an adjunctive role: a process that tests the limits of who defines crime and how to respond. Homel, Lincoln and Herd (this issue) discuss the prospects of crime prevention in indigenous communities and note how little attention has been given to questions of gender and 'ethnicity' in the extant literature. Their approach informed by developmental criminology identifies relevant risk and protective factors and shows that indigenous crime has been over-determined by more conventional approaches. The key for them is also self-determination as ownership of the process and practice of community crime prevention. For Jackson the intersection of ‘race’, class and gender in the context of the colonial legacy render the struggle to break the "cycle of violence" an especially difficult problem without the promise of restorative justice or jurisidictional autonomy Separate or autonomous self-regulation does seem an option the Canadian state [for example, Nunavut once part of the NW Territories] can contemplate within its federal structure but less likely in a centralized state such as New Zealand. For Jackson, human rights as enshrined in the Canadian Charter are the first step in mobilizing legal resources in the struggle for self-determination. Harding (this issue) in an analysis of the aftermath of the Royal Commission into Aboriginal Deaths in Custody observes that despite reductions in Aboriginal deaths in police custody, deaths in prisons are no less frequent than before the inquiry. This arose because ‘system’ approaches to reducing the risk of prison mortality were weakened by the focus on factors particular to the excessive levels of Aboriginal custody. Thus ‘Aboriginalism’ and reliance on ‘rights’ compartmentalized solutions which required generic approaches that actually address the inadequacy of prison regimes. The essays show that there has been a fundamental shift in the focus of criminological interest away from the indigenous ‘problem’ and a pre-occupation with the pathologies of indigenous crime to the pathologizing theories and criminalizing consequences of the welfare-punishment nexus aptly embedded welfare colonialism. No longer is the central ‘problem’ the deprived indigenous subject but the ‘settler’ state and the legacies of (post) colonialism. The subject of interest is the settlers and how they have conceptualized the indigenous [via Orientalism qua ‘Aboriginalism’] and mobilized the law to legitimate land theft and manage ‘race’ conflicts. The Aboriginal struggle to have law exercised in their interest is illustrated by Cuneen’s account of the Australian state's response to cultural genocide exposed in the ‘stolen generations’ inquiry: a practice relevant to all three settler states. Here denial of genocide takes on characteristics reminiscent of “techniques of neutralization” [Matza and Sykes 1957] which is conventionally applied to explain the ‘criminality’ of offenders who otherwise purport to respect the laws and values they violate. References Blagg, Harry 1997. ‘A Just measure of shame? Aboriginal Youth and Conferencing in Australia’ The British journal of Criminology, 37:481-501. Rowse, Tim (1998) White Flour, White Power: From Rations to Citizenship in Central Australia, Cambridge University Press, Melbourne. Sykes, Gresham, and David Matza (1957) ‘Techniques of Neutralization: A Theory of Delinquency’, American Sociological Review, Volume 22, pp. 667-670. Roderic Broadhurst, Hong Kong, June 1999. work_hiiinsghivhgziswrj6z6f3mfm ---- Downward mobility and Rawlsian justice Downward mobility and Rawlsian justice Govind Persad1 ! Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2017 Abstract Technological and societal changes have made downward social and economic mobility a pressing issue in real-world politics. This article argues that a Rawlsian society would not provide any special protection against downward mobility, and would act rightly in declining to provide such protection. Special treatment for the downwardly mobile can be grounded neither in Rawls’s core principles—the basic liberties, fair equality of opportunity, and the difference prin- ciple—nor in other aspects of Rawls’s theory (the concept of legitimate expectations, the idea of a life plan, the distinction between allocative and distributive justice, or the distinction between ideal and nonideal theory). Instead, a Rawlsian society is willing to sacrifice particular individuals’ ambitions and plans for the achievement of justice, and offers those who lose out from justified change no special solicitude over and above the general solicitude extended to all. Rather than guaranteeing the mainte- nance of any particular individual or group’s economic position, it provides all of its members—the upwardly mobile, the downwardly mobile, and the immobile—a form of security that is at once more generous and more limited: that they will receive the liberties, opportunities, and resources promised by the principles of justice. Keywords Social mobility ! Economic mobility ! Legitimate expectations ! Trade ! Automation ! Social change ! John Rawls Changes in labor, housing, and other markets have brought concerns about downward social and economic mobility to the forefront of political debates. & Govind Persad gpersad@jhu.edu 1 Berman Institute of Bioethics, Johns Hopkins University, 1809 Ashland Ave., Baltimore, MD 21205, USA 123 Philos Stud DOI 10.1007/s11098-017-0867-8 http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1007/s11098-017-0867-8&domain=pdf http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1007/s11098-017-0867-8&domain=pdf Globalized economic competition and labor mobility has disrupted stable social and economic positions, as has technical innovation such as the automation of tasks and the easy dissemination of digital content. However, the threat that change poses to those currently occupying these formerly stable but now precarious positions is frequently not absolute deprivation, but rather relative deprivation—and, in particular, deprivation relative not to others wealth, but rather to their own past standard of living. In this article, I argue that a broadly Rawlsian society would not provide downwardly mobile individuals with any special protection against, or compensa- tion for, the effects of social change, and that it would act rightly in not providing such protection. Rather, all members of a Rawlsian society would enjoy a secure guarantee of basic liberties, a decent social minimum, and fair opportunity to compete for positions of advantage. As an exegetical matter, Rawls’s theory offers no special assistance to those who suffer the effects of downward mobility. As a normative matter, its lack of special solicitude for the downwardly mobile is desirable and not regrettable. Rawls’s most direct discussion of downward mobility occurs in a brief comment on free trade: Persons engaged in a particular industry often find that free trade is contrary to their interests. Perhaps the industry cannot remain prosperous without tariffs or other restrictions. But if free trade is desirable from the point of view of equal citizens or of the least advantaged, it is justified even though more specific interests temporarily suffer. For we are to agree in advance to the principles of justice and their consistent application from the standpoint of certain positions. There is no way to guarantee the protection of every interest over each period of time once the situation of representative men is defined more narrowly. Having acknowledged certain principles and a certain way of applying them, we are bound to accept the consequences. This does not mean, of course, that the rigors of free trade should be allowed to go unchecked. But the arrangements for softening them are to be considered from an appropri- ately general perspective.1 Free trade may be ‘‘desirable from the point of view of equal citizens or of the least advantaged’’ because it permits workers to specialize in their most productive occupation, or drives down the cost of producing consumer goods, such as clothing, needed by all but especially by the disadvantaged. Other policy changes, as well as technical innovation, might be similarly desirable despite their disruptive effects on specific groups or industries. Policy changes such as carbon taxes or farm subsidy reforms enable society to avoid the worst effects of climate change or improve access to healthy foods. Technological advances like the Internet and the cellular phone enable individuals to more easily communicate with loved ones and bring products to market. 1 John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1999), p. 85. G. Persad 123 Yet, as Rawls observes, changes desirable from the point of view of justice frequently impose losses on particular individuals or groups. Carbon taxes may hurt coal miners. Entrepreneurs may wreak creative destruction on established firms. Trade liberalization may render assembly-line manufacturing obsolete in developed nations. Rawls recognizes the possibility that changes consistent with justice may disadvantage specific groups not only in his brief discussion of free trade, but also in his longer examination of efficiency and justice, where he observes that even if several arrangements are equally efficient—in the sense that moving from one efficient arrangement to another will always worsen the prospects of some group— we may select a more just arrangement at the expense of a particular individual or group’s prospects. To illustrate the potential breadth of downward mobility, consider six cases where economic or social changes produce downward mobility: 1) GASOLINE TAXES. The threat of climate change leads to substantially higher gasoline taxes. These taxes cause homes in exurban areas to lose much of their value; many homeowners in these areas face the prospect of needing to move, losing much of their home equity, or even foreclosure. 2) PHYSICIAN PAYMENTS. National health insurance leads to reduced payments to physicians. While those who expected to be physicians can still earn a decent living practicing medicine, their living standards are substantially reduced from what they expected. 3) FREE MARKET ETHANOL. Cheaper, more efficient sugarcane ethanol is imported from Brazil to the United States, because tariffs have been eliminated, and replaces corn-based ethanol. This lowers gasoline prices and creates jobs in the importing industry, but destroys the jobs of farmers and corn-based ethanol producers. 4) AUTOMATED TRUCKING. Automated vehicles are deployed in the trucking industry and, because of their improved safety and efficiency, largely displace human truck drivers. Former truck drivers must retrain or face income declines. 5) GOURMET TRENDS. Popular culture extols the virtues of cuisines that feature fresh vegetables and herbs. Sales of canned vegetables and precooked meals drop, and both stockholders and employees suffer economic losses. 6) INFLATION. To stimulate broader economic growth and reduce unemployment, the Federal Reserve increases the money supply, leading to higher levels of inflation. This inflation reduces the purchasing power of those holding wealth. The first three cases build on the work of theorists—Lukas Meyer, Nien-hê Hsieh, and Aaron James—who argue in favor of special protections against downward mobility, while the final three develop similar ideas in different directions. Meyer argues that ‘‘the expectation of people in the highly industrialized countries… that they will be able to emit on average what collectively will amount to their states’ current level of emissions and up to that level in the future’’ is politically, morally, and epistemically legitimate, and that their expectations constrain efforts to combat Downward mobility and Rawlsian justice 123 climate change.2 Hsieh argues that we must respect doctors’ ‘‘legitimate expecta- tions’’ of earning a pre-reform market wage.3 And James asserts that ‘‘because it seems unfair to worsen someone’s condition by $1000 merely to give someone else $1500,’’ relaxing a tariff when doing so will drive down the wages of some domestic workers requires a weighty justification.4 These cases illustrate that downward mobility encompasses a variety of different economic causes and effects: it can include loss of firms’ capital (INFLATION); of homeowners’ wealth (GASOLINE TAXES); or of labor income (PHYSICIAN PAYMENTS, FREE MARKET ETHANOL, AUTOMATED TRUCKING). And it can stem from technical innovation (AUTOMATED TRUCKING), consumer preferences (GOURMET TRENDS), legal reform (INFLATION, FREE MARKET ETHANOL, PHYSICIAN PAYMENTS), or a combination of law with natural phenomena (GASOLINE TAXES). Downward mobility’s implications also cut in complex ways across political classifications. For instance, thinkers on the right might argue that we must compensate or protect the losers in INFLATION, but not in AUTOMATED TRUCKING; meanwhile, many on the left would advocate for the reverse. In contrast, I argue that they are all amenable to the same analysis. I see no decisive reason to be more concerned about changes that policymakers bring about than those they fail to prevent, changes resulting from trade rather than technical innovation or shifting consumer preferences, or changes threatening income rather than wealth (or vice versa). Similarly, I reject Hayek’s well-known suggestion that the effects of a spontaneous market order on individuals—as in GOURMET TRENDS—are outside the scope of justice.5 Our ability to limit the effects of a ‘‘spontaneous’’ market order by compensating the losers in GOURMET TRENDS entails that whether or not to compensate them is a question of justice, rather than a question outside justice. This view about the broad scope of justice finds additional support in the fact that the major political and social institutions of a Rawlsian society include the market and family as well as the state. Therefore, while I agree with Hayek’s conclusion that we should not compensate the losers in GOURMET TRENDS, my agreement stems not from a belief that the market’s results are uncriticizable but instead from the belief that merely suffering an economic setback—whether due to the market, nature, or just laws, and whether the setback constitutes lost income or lost wealth—does not, without more, generate an entitlement to aid at public expense. While Rawls, like Meyer, Hsieh, and James, recognized the burdens that institutional change can place on individuals and industries, his conclusions about what we should do to ease those burdens diverge from theirs. In the next two sections, I consider and argue against interpretations of Rawls’s theory of justice that would justify special protections against downward mobility. I first consider 2 Lukas H. Meyer and Pranay Sanklecha, ‘‘Individual Expectations and Climate Justice,’’ Analyse & Kritik 2 (2011): 449–471, at p. 468. 3 Nien-hê Hsieh, ‘‘Moral Desert, Fairness and Legitimate Expectations in the Market,’’ Journal of Political Philosophy 8 (2000): 91–114, at p. 103. 4 Aaron James, Fairness in Practice (New York: Oxford University Press, 2012), p. 207. 5 See F.A. Hayek, Law, Legislation, and Liberty, vol. 2: The Mirage of Social Justice (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1976), p. 33. G. Persad 123 whether special measures for the downwardly mobile could be grounded in Rawls’s principles of justice: (a) The basic liberties (b) Fair equality of opportunity (c) The difference principle I argue that none of these require special treatment for those experiencing downward mobility. Rather, they recommend providing a more general form of protection to all members of society. I then consider whether other aspects of Rawls’s theory might support special treatment for the downwardly mobile where his core principles do not. These include: (d) The concept of legitimate expectations (e) The idea of a life plan (f) The distinction between allocative and distributive justice (I cover these potential sources for special treatment in descending order of their plausibility.) I argue that these concepts either do not support special measures for the downwardly mobile or are subordinate to the principles of justice. Last, although my focus is primarily on how Rawlsian ideal theory would approach downward mobility, I close with a discussion of how the distinction between ideal and nonideal theory might bear on questions concerning downward mobility. Ultimately, although Rawlsian justice lacks a separate and distinct theoretical framework for approaching problems of institutional change,6 it offers a very simple and normatively attractive way of addressing institutional change: offer those who lose out from justified change no special solicitude over and above the general solicitude extended to all. All members of a Rawlsian society, including those who lose from social change, those who gain, and those who never had much to lose in the first place, enjoy the same social guarantees: the basic liberties, fair equality of opportunity, and the difference principle. A Rawlsian society does not guarantee the maintenance of any particular individual or group’s economic position. Rather, it provides all of its members—the upwardly mobile, the downwardly mobile, and the immobile—a basic structure in which they can lead a fulfilling and vibrant life. While a Rawlsian society is willing to sacrifice the details of particular individuals’ ambitions and plans to the achievement of justice, it provides individuals a guarantee against being deprived of social goods or arbitrarily controlled by the powerful. This conclusion is particularly interesting because it suggests that an influential strand of thought in analytic political philosophy—Rawls’s theory of distributive justice—provides an important insight into how to respond to social change. Some have recently suggested that Rawls’s theory of justice provides us a framework for 6 Allen Buchanan, ‘‘Distributive Justice and Legitimate Expectations,’’ Philosophical Studies 28 (1975): 419–425, at p. 425. Downward mobility and Rawlsian justice 123 responding to the growth of real-world inequality.7 I believe Rawls’s theory is likewise relevant to currently pressing political questions surrounding downward mobility. And my examination of Rawls’s theory suggests that it has implications that are more revisionary for these questions than it might initially seem. 1 Downward mobility and Rawlsian principles Rawls’s theory of justice involves two principles, which are presented in order of priority. The first principle is that each individual is entitled to a set of basic liberties that is compatible with equal liberties for others. The second principle is that inequalities in social and economic circumstances, for example higher pay for workers in certain jobs, must be attached to positions that are substantively open to all (fair equality of opportunity) and must be to the greatest benefit of the worst-off group in society (the difference principle). In what follows, I separate the second principle into its two parts, which Rawls also presents in order of priority. 1.1 The basic liberties Downward mobility would clearly be objectionable were it to deprive individuals of their most fundamental entitlement—their basic liberties. But it poses, in itself, no threat to most basic liberties. Only if it leads to absolute deprivation will it threaten political rights, liberty of conscience, and physical integrity. The only basic liberty that dropping from, say, the upper middle to the working class might threaten is the ‘‘right to hold personal property and freedom from arbitrary arrest and seizure as defined by the concept of the rule of law.’’8 However, downward mobility does not violate the rule of law. Nor does it deprive individuals of protected personal property. 1.1.1 The rule of law Alexander Brown argues that the rule of law ‘‘requires that public bodies manage changes in ways that respect the legitimate expectations of those adversely affected.’’9 Because the rule of law is a basic liberty, lexically subordinate principles such as fair equality of opportunity or the difference principle cannot be realized at its expense. On this interpretation, therefore, legitimate expectations would constrain distributive and egalitarian goals. 7 Joshua Cohen (with Seth Resler), ‘‘Occupation as Fairness: What John Rawls Would Make of the Occupy Movement,’’ Boston Review (Nov. 17, 2011), http://bostonreview.net/joshua-cohen-seth-resler- john-rawls-occupy-wall-street; Steven Mazie, ‘‘Rawls on Wall Street,’’ The New York Times (Oct. 21, 2011), http://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2011/10/21/rawls-on-wall-street/. 8 Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 53. 9 Alexander Brown, ‘‘Rawls, Buchanan, and the Legal Doctrine of Legitimate Expectations,’’ Social Theory and Practice 38 (2012): 617–644, at p. 634. G. Persad 123 http://bostonreview.net/joshua-cohen-seth-resler-john-rawls-occupy-wall-street http://bostonreview.net/joshua-cohen-seth-resler-john-rawls-occupy-wall-street http://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2011/10/21/rawls-on-wall-street/ Brown’s understanding of the rule of law runs contrary to Rawls’s. As Brown himself concedes, Rawls’s definition of the rule of law comprises only a few basic ideas, namely the precept that ought implies can; the precept that similar cases be treated similarly; the precept that there is no offense without law; [and] the precepts of natural justice, including the precept that there is due process in law.10 Importantly, this list excludes substantive protection for expectations. Given the limitations that an overexpansive understanding of the rule of law would place on efforts to realize the difference and equality of opportunity principles, this exclusion was no oversight. Further, the descriptive fact that some nations’ legal cultures explicitly protect substantive expectations does not provide decisive reason either to read Rawls as defining the rule of law to protect expectations or to treat such protection as normatively justified or required.11 Ellen Frankel Paul likewise argues that rule of law considerations require that the protection of individuals’ expectations trump fair equality of opportunity and the difference principle. She argues that [a]n explicit component of the first principle of justice, that which decrees equal compatible liberties for all, is the traditional notion of the rule of law which dictates in part: (1) that laws be enacted in good faith and that this good faith be recognized by those subject to the enactments; (2) that similar cases be treated similarly, and (3) that laws ought not be retroactive. Rawls terms this ‘‘justice as regularity,’’ and he concludes that the rules of a legal system ought to serve to organize social behavior by providing a basis of legitimate expectations.12 The first two prongs are irrelevant: downward mobility frequently stems from legislative decisions made in good faith that treat similar cases similarly. Meanwhile, even if the prohibition on retroactivity protects those who suffer losses from institutional changes, Paul misinterprets that prohibition. Rawls requires only that retroactive criminal laws be used sparingly, and does not prohibit the retroactivity of civil legislation.13 A proposal like GASOLINE TAXES or a direct increase in property taxes, though it may seriously set back a landowner’s interests, does not violate that landowner’s basic liberties. 10 Ibid., p. 637. 11 Contrary to ibid., pp. 637–643. Buchanan, ‘‘Distributive Justice and Legitimate Expectations,’’ 422, agrees with me that the ‘‘rule of law itself appears too lean to provide what is required’’ for the protection of legitimate expectations. 12 Ellen Frankel Paul, ‘‘The Just Takings Issue,’’ Environmental Ethics 3 (1981): 309–328, at p. 326. 13 Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 209. Christopher Bertram similarly worries that Rawlsian justice will conflict with the ‘‘norm of prospectivity,’’ though Bertram—like me and unlike Paul—ultimately prioritizes justice over prospectivity. Bertram, ‘‘The Problem of Rawlsian Transition,’’ posting to Crooked Timber, Aug. 7, 2012, http://crookedtimber.org/2012/08/07/the-problem-of-rawlsian-transition/. Downward mobility and Rawlsian justice 123 http://crookedtimber.org/2012/08/07/the-problem-of-rawlsian-transition/ Paul likewise misconstrues the idea of justice as regularity, which prohibits invidious bias against individuals or groups as well as individual corruption.14 Although Rawlsian justice as regularity ‘‘supports and secures legitimate expec- tations,’’ such expectations must be consistent with the principles of justice, including the difference principle.15 The rule of law principle does not elevate the protection of expectations simpliciter—as opposed to legitimate expectations—to the level of a basic liberty. Although Rawls flirts with the idea of endorsing some broader substantive protection of good-faith—rather than objectively legitimate— expectations as part of justice as regularity, he ultimately treats achieving just social institutions as more important than protecting individual expectations.16 A further reason to doubt that the rule of law protects against downward mobility derives from the requirement that laws be democratically justified by public reasons. In a Rawlsian society, no individual will simply be expropriated at one stroke by kingly fiat.17 Rather, any change must be implemented through a democratic process in which decisions are justified to those affected. The requirement of democratic justification also serves to provide notice to those whose holdings might be affected by a change in law. For instance, before imposing a gasoline tax, a legislature must take up and debate the proposed tax, putting potentially affected interests on notice of the change and giving them the opportunity to argue against or prepare for the effects of potential changes. No reasonably attentive member of society, even if she loses out in the democratic process, will be blindsided by its effects.18 1.1.2 Property Some commentators have interpreted Rawls’s right to personal property as a purely procedural right that would not justify ensuring that individuals can continue owning and using particular objects, while others interpret the right to personal property as protecting only a decent minimum.19 Neither of these interpretations justify special protection against downward mobility. The right to personal property will only justify protection against downward mobility if interpreted to protect the use and possession of all the personal property one happens to have. Even such a maximal understanding of the right, however, 14 Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 207; ibid., 51. 15 On this point, see, for instance, Christine Swanton, ‘‘Is the Difference Principle a Principle of Justice?’’ Mind 90 (1981): 415–421, at p. 418. 16 Ibid. at 51–52. 17 See, for example, Rawls, A Theory of Justice, at 241. I thank Samuel Freeman for helping me to see this point. 18 On this point, see also Jeremy Waldron, The Rule of Law and The Measure of Property (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012), p. 36–41. 19 For the procedural interpretation, see H.L.A. Hart, ‘‘Rawls on Liberty and its Priority,’’ University of Chicago Law Review 40 (1973): 534–555, at p. 540; Jeremy Waldron, ‘‘Nozick and Locke: Filling the Space of Rights,’’ Social Philosophy and Policy 22 (2005): 81–110, at p. 84; for the minimal interpretation, see Samuel Freeman, ‘‘Capitalism in the Classical and High Liberal Traditions,’’ Social Philosophy and Policy 28 (2011): 19–55, at p. 3. G. Persad 123 cannot justify protecting individuals against downward mobility with respect to future income or consumption. Even if expectations of continued employment or receipt of benefits can constitute a sort of property, they do not constitute personal property whose loss would undermine individuals’ independence and integrity. Nor would even the most expansive understanding of Rawlsian personal property protect expectations of receiving income from its use or rental.20 There is no personal property right to sell coal that one mines, for instance, even if the coal comes from one’s own back yard. Even a maximally broad Rawlsian right to personal property protects only the use and possession of personal property—it does not create an ironclad entitlement to all fruits of that use of personal property. Such a distinction between personal property and its fruits does not rest on any mysterious distinction between productive property and other property, but rather on the familiar distinction between a right to possess something and a right to the proceeds of that thing’s use. 1.2 Fair equality of opportunity Rawls’s concept of fair equality of opportunity requires ‘‘not merely that public offices and social positions be open in the formal sense, but that all should have a fair chance to attain them,’’ where the content of a ‘‘fair chance’’ involves there being ‘‘roughly the same prospects of culture and achievement for those similarly motivated and endowed.’’21 This idea might be employed to justify special protection against downward mobility. Imagine, for instance, that AUTOMATED TRUCKING worsens the job prospects of a truck driver compared to those of an equally motivated and endowed train operator. Protecting the truck driver against downward mobility—for instance, via special hiring preferences for truck drivers— may seem consistent with and even required by fair equality of opportunity. There are two problems with this argument. First, many interpret Rawlsian fair equality of opportunity as only requiring a ‘‘moment of equal opportunity’’ after which individuals’ opportunities may diverge.22 On this interpretation, as long as the two drivers’ prospects were equal at the moment of equal opportunity, differences in opportunity later on do not violate fair equality of opportunity. Second, special protection against downward mobility, even though it situates the truck driver and train operator similarly, gives the recently unemployed truck driver a difficult-to-justify advantage over others who are similarly motivated and endowed, such as immigrants, recent graduates, and those currently in lower-paid positions. Fair equality of opportunity may also appear to justify special protection against downward mobility on the basis that the talents and skills that current workers 20 Contrary to James W. Nickel, ‘‘Economic Liberties,’’ in The Idea of Political Liberalism: Essays on Rawls, eds. Victoria Davion and Clark Wolf (Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield, 2000): 155–175, at p. 166. 21 Rawls, Justice as Fairness, pp. 43–44. 22 See the discussion in Clare Chambers, ‘‘Each Outcome Is Another Opportunity: Problems with the Moment of Equal Opportunity,’’ Politics, Philosophy, and Economics 8 (2009): 374–400. Downward mobility and Rawlsian justice 123 acquired in the course of employment support giving them preference for positions that would use those talents. Rawls observes that ‘‘the reasons for requiring open positions are not solely, or even primarily, those of efficiency,’’ but rather that, without fair equality of opportunity, some people would be ‘‘debarred from experiencing the realization of self which comes from a skillful and devoted exercise of social duties’’ and ‘‘would be deprived of one of the main forms of human good.’’23 Such considerations might seem, for instance, to support funding job retraining programs for the recently unemployed rather than funding programs—such as elementary education—that serve the not-yet-employed. However, current workers’ interest in self-realization cannot justify protecting them against downward mobility at the expense of those who are seeking to begin their involvement in social cooperation. Doing so would violate Rawls’s admonition that social institutions should not ask already disadvantaged individuals ‘‘to accept still lower prospects of life for the sake of others.’’24 As such, although our interest in self-realization helps justify the fair equality of opportunity principle, that principle—as an equality principle—prioritizes giving each person equal access to self-realization over helping the already self-realized become even more so. Though the fair equality of opportunity principle might support state-sponsored efforts to ensure each citizen access to some form of gainful employment, it cannot support efforts to ensure that workers currently occupying particular positions remain in those positions over time. A related attempt to justify special treatment appeals to Rawls’s idea that society constitutes a ‘‘system of cooperation.’’ This argument makes the case that individuals are entitled to their present jobs, because their jobs are the way they participate in the system of cooperative activity—one’s job might be regarded as one’s ‘‘place in the cooperative scheme.’’25 This objection, however, conflates the (correct) claim that each person is entitled to some place in the cooperative scheme with the (mistaken) one that each person is entitled to maintain the same place in the cooperative scheme over time. Fair equality of opportunity justifies efforts to combat unemployment, which cuts some individuals off entirely from participation in the scheme of social production, even if allowing higher rates of unemployment would increase the consumption enjoyed by the worst-off members of society.26 Combatting unemployment, however, does not require maintaining individuals in their current positions; it only requires that each person be afforded an opportunity to contribute in some way. 23 Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 73. 24 Ibid., p. 155. 25 Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 410. 26 Cf. Robert S. Taylor, ‘‘Self-Realization and the Priority of Fair Equality of Opportunity,’’ Journal of Moral Philosophy 1.3 (2004): 333–347, at p. 338. G. Persad 123 1.3 The difference principle Downward mobility would clearly violate the difference principle if it directly worsened the worst-off positions in society. Buchanan attempts to justify efforts to prevent downward mobility on this basis: [T]he prospects of the worst off include their prospects of ascending to higher positions, of enjoying the benefits of those positions, and of being able to continue to enjoy those benefits. Maximizing their expectations, then, will require taking into account the stability of institutional arrangements, since liability to future disruptions decreases their present expectations, other things being equal.27 1.3.1 Direct effects Downward mobility would violate the difference principle if it directly worsened the worst position with no compensating indirect effects. Austerity policies that lower the income of individuals occupying the worst positions in society without indirectly compensating for that lowering, for instance, clearly violate the difference principle. However, downward mobility plays no essential part in this violation: the aftermath of a change that worsens the position of the worst-off is no more objectionable than the failure to remedy an equally bad and easily remediable status quo. In later work, Rawls further clarifies that ‘‘the least advantaged are by definition those who are born into and who remain in that group throughout their life.’’28 This definition of the least advantaged undermines Buchanan’s claim that the worst off benefit from policies that protect against downward mobility. Because the least advantaged group comprises only individuals who never move up into a higher group, that group will never directly benefit from policies that protect those who have risen against dropping back down. While the least advantaged have reason to reject a policy that irrationally or arbitrarily makes individual holdings insecure, they have nothing to lose, and much to gain, from an approach that regards protection against downward mobility as subordinate to improving the holdings of the least advantaged. 1.3.2 Indirect effects More interesting are policies that impose downward mobility on some better-off individuals while having neutral or even positive direct effects on the worst position. Examples might include INFLATION and PHYSICIAN PAYMENTS, which raise wages and lower health care costs even while reducing the economic position of physicians and creditors. Determining the compatibility of such changes with the 27 Buchanan, ‘‘Distributive Justice and Legitimate Expectations,’’ 423–424. 28 John Rawls, Collected Papers, ed. Samuel Freeman (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2001), p. 364. Downward mobility and Rawlsian justice 123 difference principle requires assessing their indirect effects on the social and economic position of the worst-off group in society. Buchanan believes that the difference principle could protection against downward mobility for the better-off because of the indirect benefits of doing so for the worst-off: [T]he knowledge that institutional arrangements were liable to revision at any time, as a result of direct application of the difference principle, might itself undermine individual security to such an extent that expectations in general, including the expectations of the worst off, were diminished.29 Assessing the indirect benefits about which Buchanan speculates would require an empirical, social-scientific investigation that is beyond our scope here. However, it is worth considering what the upshots of such social science would be. Social science can help us move from normative ideals, such as the difference principle, to policy conclusions in two ways. First, it can determine whether the possibility of downward mobility truly does exert a chilling effect on the choices of the better-off. Even in a world where social and legal arrangements were ironclad and unchanging, individual expectations would remain pervasively vulnerable to other sources of disappointment. For instance, after taking out a loan, a surgeon might suffer a disability or acquire caregiving responsibilities that make a career in surgery impossible. Yet the possibility of these disruptions does not dissuade individuals from pursuing careers in surgery; it is therefore not obvious that disruptions caused by institutional changes will do so. Second, social science can tell us about the causal pathways by which insecure expectations for the better-off translate into worse circumstances for the worst-off. Such information can help in normatively assessing who is culpable for the worsened situation of the worst-off. For instance, if the least advantaged are suffering because of a policy instituted that frequently seizes surgeons’ cars without warning in order to transfer the proceeds to the least advantaged, the policy would be culpable—surgeons cannot help the fact that they need reliable transportation to do their jobs effectively. In contrast, if the least advantaged are suffering because surgeons refuse to work unless guaranteed that their pay will remain the same, surgeons, rather than the policy, are culpable, because surgeons do not require the maintenance of their current economic status in order to do their jobs. There is a well-developed literature that attempts to identify when workers’ claims to economic incentives are objectionable.30 Demands that institutional arrangements not be changed raise similar issues to demands for wage incentives, and may be amenable to a similar analysis.31 Most importantly, even where the difference principle, because of indirect effects, justifies special protection against downward mobility, this special 29 Buchanan, ‘‘Distributive Justice and Legitimate Expectations,’’ 423–424. 30 For example, Joshua Cohen, ‘‘Taking People as They Are?’’ Philosophy & Public Affairs 30.4 (2001): 363–386. 31 Cohen describes the aim of preserving one’s current privileges in order to maintain social distance between oneself and those worse off as much more objectionable than a simple desire to gain in absolute terms. Ibid. at pp. 369–371. G. Persad 123 protection is not provided for the sake of those it protects, but the sake of the worst off. Were social science to conclude that protections against downward mobility did not optimize the position of the worst-off, the case for these protections would collapse. As such, any effort to ground protection against downward mobility in the difference principle differs fundamentally from a strategy that appeals to the basic liberties or fair equality of opportunity. The difference principle will never regard the economic status of the better-off as inviolable; at most, it will protect their economic status insofar as such protection happens to further the interests of the worst-off. 2 Downward mobility and Rawlsian concepts 2.1 Legitimate expectations Nien-hê Hsieh interprets Rawls’s concept of legitimate expectations as justifying special protection for those who experience downward mobility due to social change. He does so via the example I called PHYSICIAN PAYMENTS: Betty is a medical student in the United States who borrows $100,000 to cover the cost of her medical training with the expectation that she will be able to repay the loan once she has entered into private practice as a surgeon. As a surgeon she is legally entitled to receive the salary that will allow her to repay the loan, but at the time of taking out the loan she is not legally entitled to the prospect of becoming a surgeon. Now suppose that the government institutes a national health care system in which the amount that doctors can earn is substantially diminished relative to what they did prior to the change in the health care system.32 Hsieh asserts that ‘‘there is a sense in which fairness demands that Betty’s expectation, at least with respect to her ability to repay the loan, be fulfilled,’’ and that ‘‘[h]er expectation of being able to repay the loan can be understood as a legitimate expectation, even though she was never legally entitled to the prospect of becoming a surgeon.’’33 Betty’s case may arouse our sympathy. But I disagree with Hsieh that considerations of fairness entitle Betty to have her expectations met, because her expectations, though strongly held, are not legitimate. Legitimate expectations cannot arise purely through custom.34 The new health care system must be consistent with the basic liberties and fair equality of opportunity, and must maximize the position of the worst off. It is easy to see how the new health care system Hsieh describes would be consistent with the difference principle: imagine 32 Hsieh, ‘‘Moral Desert, Fairness and Legitimate Expectations in the Market,’’ p. 103. 33 Ibid., p. 103. Hsieh also states, at p. 104, that Betty’s ‘‘expectations are legitimate… because they arise within the context of following institutionally specified rules.’’. 34 See Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 252. Downward mobility and Rawlsian justice 123 that, for instance, the money saved by paying physicians less would permit greater access to medicines or lower out-of-pocket costs for the most disadvantaged patients. Refusing to implement the new system because of its effects on Betty’s expectations would impose greater costs on the worst-off members of society, and the government would therefore violate the difference principle—and hence act unjustly—were it to fulfill her expectations. Betty’s expectations thus cannot be legitimate. Approaching Betty’s case through the lens of contract theory helps clarify why her expectations lack normative force. When private citizens contract with one another, they accept that certain ‘‘escape conditions’’ established in contract law— such as mistakes of fact or law, impossibility or impracticability of performance, or substantive unconscionability—could release the parties from their legal duties to perform. Analogously, an individual receiving a promise from the state in a Rawlsian society cannot expect that the promise be kept come what may. Instead, a Rawlsian state’s contracts with private parties include a moral, rather than legal, ‘‘escape condition’’: there is no obligation to fulfill the expectations of private parties, even expectations the state has encouraged, in cases where doing so would be inconsistent with a principle of justice. A system of rules must be just in order for the expectations it authorizes to be legitimate.35 The idea that rights or duties contain an ‘‘escape condition’’ is by no means unique to Rawls’s theory. Another example is what Robert Nozick calls the ‘‘Lockean proviso,’’ which prohibits anyone from appropriating property in a way that does not leave ‘‘enough and as good…in common for others.’’36 As Nozick observes, the Lockean proviso will sometimes disrupt property-holders’ expecta- tions: even if a water-hole owner could not have foreseen all other water-holes drying up, his expectation of unlimited profits from the water hole goes beyond what his property right can support.37 Because of the structure of Rawls’s theory of justice, in particular that of the difference principle, an escape condition will much more frequently come into play in Rawls’s theory than in Nozick’s. The Lockean proviso is a satisficing principle: it merely requires parties to a contract to leave enough for others. In contrast, the difference principle—though it plays a structurally parallel role to the Lockean proviso—is an optimizing principle: it requires that the worst position be made as good as possible. Because it is an optimizing principle, the difference principle typically leaves no spare resources for the fulfillment of contracts. A Rawlsian state’s contractual commitments will therefore only be relevant when the principles of justice are neutral between two alternatives. If fulfilling Betty’s expectations would have no net impact on the worst-off position, the state should fulfill her expectations for her sake. But if fulfilling them would hurt the worst-off, 35 Ibid., p. 207. 36 Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), pp. 175–176. 37 Ibid., p. 180. G. Persad 123 the state should not fulfill her expectations.38 And if fulfilling them would lead to a better position for the worst off, the state should fulfill them, but for the sake of the worst-off rather than for her sake. Perhaps Betty’s claims could be given slightly more purchase by also treating them as relevant in situations where we are radically uncertain which policies will optimize the worst position, or where we regard two policies as on a par—rather than identical—with respect to their effects on the worst position. But I doubt such a revision would extend her claims’ reach to many more cases. What I have said is fully consistent with our regretting that Betty’s expectations go unfulfilled, and even with our apologizing to Betty for her having to bear the brunt of what we do. But we can regret an unavoidable injury, and apologize for it, while recognizing that justice requires it. This would be clear in a case where fulfilling Betty’s expectations required violating someone’s bodily integrity or depriving them of their right to vote—in such a case, though we might regret having to upset Betty’s expectations, we would not treat Betty’s expectations as overriding those important interests. Indeed, if Betty possesses the sense of justice that Rawls posits the citizens of a just Rawlsian state would, she would not press her claims when their fulfillment would be inconsistent with the fulfillment of principles of justice. She would regard demanding that she be paid what she had originally expected as analogous to demanding the enforcement of an unconscionable contract. Even if the contract might have seemed unexceptional when made, she recognizes that the needs of the worst-off now override the fulfillment of her expectations. At bottom, Hsieh’s and others’ invocation of legitimate expectations as limits on the pursuit of justice reflects an implicit rejection of the maximizing force of the difference principle, and potentially the fair equality of opportunity principle as well, in favor of similar satisficing principles: a ‘‘decent minimum’’ or ‘‘sufficiency of opportunity’’ principle. If fulfilling Betty’s expectations meant violating someone’s bodily integrity or abrogating her right to vote, the plausibility of the escape condition would be obvious. But that fulfilling Betty’s expectations would fail to maximize the worst position, or would prevent the opportunities of those similarly talented and motivated from being truly equal, may not motivate the escape condition’s plausibility as fully. Rawls discusses weaker distributive principles such as the decent minimum principle in his later work, where he suggests that the satisficing analogues of the difference principle and fair equality of opportunity are constitutional essentials, whereas his original principles themselves—while still principles of justice—are not constitutional essentials: While some principle of opportunity is a constitutional essential—for example, a principle requiring an open society, one with careers open to talents (to use the eighteenth-century phrase)—fair equality of opportunity 38 See Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 68 (‘‘A scheme is unjust when the higher expectations, one or more of them, are excessive. If these expectations were decreased, the situation of the least favored would be improved.’’). Downward mobility and Rawlsian justice 123 requires more than that, and is not counted a constitutional essential. Similarly, although a social minimum providing for the basic needs of all citizens is also a constitutional essential, the difference principle is more demanding and is not so regarded.39 In a society that adopts the satisficing alternative to Rawls’s original principles (the careers-open-to-talents principle of opportunity, or the decent minimum principle of distributive justice), the state’s contractual commitments will more often justify compensation rather than mere apology. However—as the earlier example of the Lockean proviso indicates—these alternative principles will still sometimes conflict with contractual duties. Buchanan agrees with me that, within Rawlsian justice, principles of justice constrain what counts as a legitimate expectation. But, unlike me, Buchanan regards this as objectionably demanding: [A]s previously just Rawlsian basic structures become unjust instantaneously in the light of new information about how to maximize the benefit of the worst off, so previously legitimate Rawlsian expectations lose their legitimacy just as instantaneously.40 Buchanan then considers two examples where expectations lose legitimacy— including one, almost identical to Hsieh’s, that involves the disrupted expectations of healthcare workers—and goes on to assert that ‘‘the strongest grievance of a person who is disadvantaged by such institutional changes is not simply that his wants have been thwarted. His functioning as a rational planner and executor of long-range plans has been undercut by his society’s attempts to continue to satisfy the difference principle.’’41 Buchanan, however, simply describes prevailing expectations as ‘‘legitimate’’ without explaining why these expectations are normatively legitimate, rather than merely strongly held, and without justifying his claim that disrupted expectations render planning impossible. An individual in a Rawlsian society must be prepared to adjust her plans in response to the demands of justice: such willingness to adjust one’s plans is part of having a sense of justice. Functioning as a rational planner does not plausibly require the ability to perfectly predict one’s future occupation and holdings, or even to do so within a narrow range.42 Although a just Rawlsian society offers no assurance that individuals will enjoy (or suffer) their current material position come what may, it provides the more normatively important assurances of equal basic liberties, fair equality of opportunity to compete for 39 Rawls, Justice as Fairness, pp. 47–48. 40 Buchanan, ‘‘Distributive Justice and Legitimate Expectations,’’ p. 421. 41 Ibid. See also the similar claim in Joel Feinberg, ‘‘Rawls and Intuitionism,’’ in Norman Daniels, Reading Rawls (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1989), 117. Feinberg complains that ‘‘[t]o change the rules in the middle of the game, even when those rules were not altogether fair, will disappoint the honest expectations of those whose prior commitments and life plans were made in genuine reliance on the continuance of the old rules.’’. 42 Andrei Marmor, ‘‘The Rule of Law and Its Limits,’’ Law and Philosophy 23 (2004): 1–42, at p. 23. G. Persad 123 positions of advantage, and a social minimum of primary goods. Such assurances are amply sufficient for the pursuit of a rational plan of life. Indeed, institutional reforms designed to better realize justice can not only be consistent with rational planning, but also enrich the goodness of a life. Ronald Dworkin suggests what he calls the ‘‘challenge model’’ of a good life, on which living a good life requires appropriately grappling with the challenges of living well, rather than amassing some sum of goods or pleasures. On the challenge model, ‘‘a good life is a life suited to the circumstances that justice requires,’’ which entails that life is enriched rather than constrained by the restriction that one may use only the resources that one can justly claim: It would be bizarre to declare, as our considered moral judgment, that it is appropriate for people each to have a fair share of resources, defined in some particular way, and not also to think, in making an ethical judgment about what circumstances we should treat as appropriate in deciding what life would be good for us, that fair circumstances, so defined, are the appropriate ones…. We must set the resource parameters of a life well lived, so far as we can, so that these respect our sense of justice.43 Dworkin goes on to suggest that someone’s life goes worse, rather than better, to the extent that he is better-off economically than justice allows. This factor could conceivably be counterbalanced by others: for Dworkin, unlike Rawls, justice is not prior to goodness. Nor is it an inescapable requirement of a good life. Rather, justice rather is an important, but overridable, constituent of a good life. Still, it would take an extraordinary circumstance for the goodness of enjoying great wealth to outweigh the badness of a life of injustice. 2.2 Life planning and the Aristotelian principle Where the realization of principles of justice conflicts with individuals’ particular plans of life, Rawls’s account requires that the plans and not the principles give way. Plans of life fall within the theory of the good, not the theory of the right, and a Rawlsian society prioritizes the right (justice) over the good (life plans). So long as an individual remains able to pursue some rational plan of life after her original expectations are disrupted, her expectations do not restrict a Rawlsian society’s efforts in pursuit of justice. Furthermore, this conclusion need not be as burdensome as it may initially appear. In a Rawlsian society, ‘‘each individual has a rational plan of life,’’44 and such plans enable individuals to achieve happy lives.45 Social and institutional change may threaten individuals’ ability to carry plans through. While institutional change can threaten good fortune, it can also free individuals from bad fortune. But Rawls—in contrast with the priority he gives to raising the worst-off up in his theory 43 Ronald Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2002), p. 265. 44 Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 80. 45 Ibid., p. 359. Downward mobility and Rawlsian justice 123 of the right—suggests that the preservation or increase of good fortune matters as much to a successful life than the avoidance of bad fortune.46 According to the Aristotelian Principle, ‘‘other things equal, human beings enjoy the exercise of their realized capacities (their innate or trained abilities), and this enjoyment increases the more the capacity is realized, or the greater its complexity.’’47 This principle will tend to make downward mobility more painful, because once one has enjoyed the pleasures of exercising superior skill, the exercise of more basic skills will seem less satisfying. However, life plans are subordinate to the realization of justice. Rightness (the fulfillment of principles of justice) has priority over goodness (life plans): ‘‘Our way of life, whatever our particular circumstances, must always conform to the principles of justice that are arrived at independently.’’48 While plans of life may be relevant in cases where the principles of justice are in equipoise between two alternatives, just as expectations can be relevant in such cases, the principles of justice override the plans of individuals whenever the two conflict. Though downward mobility may temporarily frustrate individuals, other remarks of Rawls’s suggest that downward mobility is not as onerous as it might appear, because individuals are capable of adapting to institutional change: They do not think of themselves as inevitably bound to, or as identical with, the pursuit of any particular complex of fundamental interests that they may have at any given time, although they want the right to advance such interests (provided they are admissible). Rather, free persons conceive of themselves as beings who can revise and alter their final ends and who give first priority to preserving their liberty in these matters.49 Rather than choosing to pursue inflexible plans that require the accumulation of specific, costly material goods, individuals in a Rawlsian society will pursue more malleable plans that incorporate values compatible with the realization of principles of justice—they will seek, for instance, ‘‘meaningful work and social cooperation,’’ rather than developing attachments to lives as highly paid surgeons or bankers.50 Even if swings up and down upset individuals’ plans, such swings are not properly described as catastrophic because they do not deprive individuals of basic liberties, equality of opportunity, or access to primary social goods. Indeed, as the discussion of Dworkin’s ‘‘challenge model’’ suggests, dealing constructively with the challenge that social and economic change presents may be part of what makes a life good. Individuals in a Rawlsian society will also choose plans that keep options open and allow for long-term revision. Those who can only pursue a single plan of life 46 Ibid., pp. 369–370. 47 Ibid., p. 374. 48 Ibid., p. 394–395. 49 Ibid., p. 131–132. 50 Ibid., p. 373. G. Persad 123 will be exceedingly rare—though not entirely absent.51 Furthermore, individuals should be aware not only that their personal plans may require revision, but also that social institutions may change in order to better realize principles of justice. (The possibility of institutional revision is clear from the opening page of A Theory of Justice, where Rawls asserts that ‘‘laws and institutions no matter how efficient and well-arranged must be reformed or abolished if they are unjust.’’52). Recognizing the priority of right over good also indicates that a Rawlsian society will limit certain forms of institutional change, though it will do so for the sake of justice rather than for the sake of preventing downward mobility. For instance, if science suggested that a technical innovation—such as a new method of extracting fossil fuels—will likely lead to long-term economic losses, a Rawlsian society would resist that innovation, though for the sake of society as a whole rather than for the sake of protecting those whose jobs that innovation would threaten. A Rawlsian society has no intrinsic bias toward change or stability—it neither preserves the status quo nor praises its disruption—but only a bias toward justice. Ultimately, it is difficult to believe that institutional change undermines workers’ status as rational agents. Rather, individuals can form plans of life compatible with a changing economy, secure in the knowledge that they enjoy basic liberties, equality of opportunity, and a decent social minimum. 2.3 Distribution, allocation, and pure procedural justice Rawls defines allocative justice, which is is inappropriate for goods produced via social cooperation, as the ‘‘problem of how a given bundle of commodities is to be distributed, or allocated, among various individuals whose particular needs, desires, and preferences are known to us, and who have not cooperated in any way to produce these commodities.’’53 In contrast, distributive justice focuses on background institutions and does not directly provide answers to questions about which individuals should hold which resources. It might therefore seem that distributive justice prohibits the imposition of downward mobility that disturbs individual holdings in service of justice. However, although distributive justice precludes the direct employment of Rawlsian principles of justice to determine which individuals should receive resources in specific situations, legislators clearly are supposed to apply Rawlsian principles when making policy choices about free trade, responses to climate change, or taxation.54 Applying the difference principle, for example, will entail the design of social institutions that inevitably disturb individual holdings. Understanding this defuses David Schmidtz’s complaint that the need for ‘‘adjustments in the basic structure’’ vitiates Rawls’s claim that the difference principle does not require continuous and capricious interference with private 51 Ibid., p. 380. 52 Ibid., p. 3. 53 Rawls, Justice as Fairness, p. 50. 54 Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 175. Downward mobility and Rawlsian justice 123 transactions.55 While Schmidtz is right that a Rawlsian society would likely indeed engage in continuous interference with people’s transactions, at least if we follow Schmidtz in understanding any societal decision that affects the value of individual holdings as an interference, it would not engage in capricious interference. To see why, return to INFLATION. A Rawlsian society could, and indeed likely would, adopt a monetary policy, which involves taking actions that affect rates of inflation as well as the exchange rate of its national currency. The worth of individuals’ holdings would then be subject to continuous adjustment as inflation and exchange rates vary over time, and these adjustments would be justified—and consistent with pure procedural justice—insofar as they optimally realized the principles of justice.56 INFLATION indicates that continuous interference is not obviously objectionable as long as it is not capricious interference. And a Rawlsian constitutional democracy would base its fiscal policy not on the caprice of unaccountable administrators but on legislative, executive, and judicial decisions that must in turn be justified in a democratic process by appeal to public reasons and principles of justice. A Rawlsian society’s implementation of monetary policy, for instance, would not be carried out on an allocative, transaction-by-transaction basis, but rather at the level of the basic structure, which ensures that individuals are subject to the same laws and are free from arbitrary and unaccountable power. Indeed, Rawls argues that efforts to protect particular individuals and groups would hamper, rather than advance, the achievement of justice.57 Pure procedural justice, as Rawls understands it, requires us to focus on the benefits and burdens of institutional change from the point of view of society in general, rather than considering the specific impacts on each individual the policy burdens or benefits. While individual impacts matter when ensuring that policies do not violate basic liberties, if some policy is broadly fair—if it best accords with fair equality of opportunity, the difference principle, and the basic liberties—the burdens it imposes on specific individuals cannot justify refusing to adopt that policy or restricting its effects. Rawlsian justice therefore has adequate resources to answer Schmidtz’s concern about ‘‘‘necessary adjustments’ that signal to citizens that their labor is a political football and they are to that extent governed by men, not law.’’58 Although policy choices in a Rawlsian democracy may subject individuals to downward mobility, these choices reflect the effects of legitimate laws rather than arbitrariness or caprice. 55 David Schmidtz, Elements of Justice (New York: Cambridge, 2005), p. 200. 56 For different approaches to the reconciliation of redistribution and pure procedural justice, compare Joshua Cohen, ‘‘Pluralism and Proceduralism,’’ Chicago-Kent Law Review 69 (1993), 589–618, at p. 597 n. 44, with Jeremy Waldron, ‘‘The Rule of Law in Contemporary Liberal Theory,’’ in G.W. Smith (ed.) Liberalism: Rights, Property and Markets (New York: Routledge, 2002), p. 103. 57 Rawls, A Theory of Justice, at p. 76. 58 Schmidtz, Elements of Justice, p. 200. G. Persad 123 Hayek advances a different argument based on pure procedural justice, which makes the case that if social arrangements and announced systems of public rules were just in the past, they remain just later on regardless of their consequences.59 On this view, rules and institutions that are just when formed never need to prove their ongoing compatibility with justice: rather, they inherit their current justice from their justice at inception. Such an understanding of the justice of rules and institutions would parallel Nozick’s view that distributions are just in virtue of their history rather than in virtue of how they distribute resources among individuals.60 This understanding of justice not only appears implausibly rigid, but fails as an interpretation of Rawls’s view. In A Theory of Justice, Rawls explicitly asserts that adjustments are required even under ideal circumstances.61 Rawls believes that a well-ordered society can be stable even while updating its basic structure and public rules in order to maintain or better realize the principles of justice in light of newly discovered facts and changing circumstances.62 A rule’s being initially just, for Rawls, does not render it eternally just. As such, in a Rawlsian society, individuals should form their social and economic expectations with the knowledge that the currently prevailing rules are subject to adjustment in service of justice. A society in which the basic structure never required adjustment would not be more just than a Rawlsian ideal society. Rather, it would be beyond justice, and outside the scope of Rawls’s discussion. 3 Conclusion I have argued that, in an ideal Rawlsian society, individuals would willingly accept the more valuable guarantee that they will be protected by the principles of justice in exchange for sacrificing the less valuable guarantee that their holdings will not be disturbed by downward mobility. This argument suggests a direction for further research, focused on how downward mobility should be addressed in a nonideal society where the principles of justice are not fully honored.63 Though Rawls explicitly states that concerns about disrupted expectations do not justify resisting a move from nonideal to ideal circumstances,64 the treatment of downward mobility under circumstances that will remain nonideal regardless of how downward mobility is addressed poses more complex questions. 59 See Waldron, ‘‘The Rule of Law in Contemporary Liberal Theory,’’ 103, and more generally Andrew Lister, ‘‘The ‘Mirage’ of Social Justice: Hayek Against (and for) Rawls,’’ Critical Review 25 (2013): 409–444. 60 Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia, 150–51. 61 Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 285. 62 Ibid., p. 401. 63 Cf. Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue, p. 265 (‘‘Once we accept that the best life means a life responding well to the right circumstances, and that the right circumstances are circumstances of justice, we become aware of how difficult it is to lead anything like the right life when circumstances are far from just.’’). 64 Rawls, Collected Papers, p. 251. Downward mobility and Rawlsian justice 123 Where social change cannot bring about justice but can only achieve an improvement in nonideal circumstances, some argue that individuals may allowably regard the burdens of downward mobility as counting against, though not invariably prohibiting, changes that would make social arrangements more just.65 Rawls himself observes that principles of justice may not apply in the same way—or at all—in nonideal contexts, which indicates that the balance between Rawlsian principles and the prevention of downward mobility might, in nonideal contexts, tilt toward the latter.66 On the other hand, under nonideal circumstances, individuals frequently owe the holdings they hope to protect to their own, or others’, failure to comply with the principles of justice.67 For this reason, Rawls suggests elsewhere that the imposition of social change may be acceptable under nonideal circum- stances if it moves society toward more just (though still nonideal) arrangements that improve conditions for the least advantaged.68 Ultimately, because nonideal conditions weaken individuals’ claims to their current circumstances while also weakening the guarantees they would receive after social change, assessing the proper treatment of downward mobility under nonideal conditions requires further analysis. This project’s discussion of downward mobility within ideal theory represents one starting point for such analysis, though there is no straightforward algorithm for how movement away from ideal theory affects the applicability of arguments originally developed in an ideal-theory context. In sum, an ideal Rawlsian society countenances social and economic change, even change that imposes downward mobility on individuals, when that change furthers the achievement of justice. However, that Rawls’s theory descriptively does not protect against downward mobility may seem like a reason to amend Rawlsian justice to add an additional principle that supports shielding individuals from downward mobility.69 My project, however, has been to argue not only that Rawlsian justice excludes special protection against downward mobility, but also that its choice not to do so is normatively attractive. I conclude by reiterating the latter point. Beliefs that Rawlsian justice must be amended to protect individuals against downward mobility stem ultimately from two misplaced fears—the fears that downward mobility will be imposed through despotism and lead to destitution. But Rawls’s principles of justice are amply sufficient to achieve a just society; an additional principle protecting against downward mobility would prove counter- productive and excessively conservative. 65 Marcus Arvan, ‘‘First Steps Toward a Non-Ideal Theory of Justice,’’ Ethics and Global Politics 7 (2014): 95–117, at pp. 104–107; Leslie Pickering Francis, ‘‘Age Rationing Under Conditions of Injustice,’’ in Rosamond Rhodes et al. eds., Medicine and Social Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), p. 274. 66 Rawls, A Theory of Justice, pp. 215–216. I am grateful to an anonymous referee for this reference and for prompting me to attend more closely to the case of downward mobility within ideal theory. 67 See Christopher Bertram, ‘‘Cosmopolitanism and Inequality,’’ Res Publica 12 (2006): 327–336, at p. 334. 68 See Rawls, A Theory of Justice, p. 218. 69 Andreas Føllesdal, ‘‘Union Citizenship: Unpacking the Beast of Burden,’’ Law and Philosophy 20 (2001), 329. G. Persad 123 The fear of despotism equates downward mobility with change imposed for reasons that are at best arbitrary and at worst self-serving and corrupt.70 But a Rawlsian constitutional democracy already has safeguards that prevent the imposition of policies for arbitrary, self-serving, or corrupt reasons. Further, to the extent that classical liberal critics like Schmidtz are concerned that these safeguards are insufficient to forestall the improper deployment of power, focusing concern on policies that impose downward mobility seems misguided. Such a focus would leave those attempting to form new plans at the mercy of arbitrary regulations while those with longstanding, settled expectations are kept secure against abuses of power. Meanwhile, the fear of destitution equates downward mobility with a total dismantling of self-respect and even of rational agency.71 But a Rawlsian society provides ample opportunity for rational planning. Individuals who experience downward mobility can stably and legitimately expect to enjoy a decent social minimum, fair equality of opportunity, and equal basic liberties as they revise their plans and projects in light of new circumstances. Such a society is far preferable to one that exhaustively protects existing plans against any disruption while leaving others without sufficient liberties, opportunities, and resources to even begin making—let alone acting on—plans of their own. Acknowledgements I am grateful to Debra Satz, Joshua Cohen, Eamonn Callan, Mark Kelman, Jorah Dannenberg, Collin Anthony, RJ Leland, Samuel Freeman, Nien-hê Hsieh, Shim Reza, and an anonymous referee at Philosophical Studies for written comments and detailed discussion. Thanks also to audiences at the 2012 National Endowment for the Humanities Summer Seminar on Liberty, Equality, and Justice; the 2012 Harvard Graduate Conference in Political Theory; and the 2014 Ethics and Politics, Ancient and Modern workshop at Stanford University. References Arvan, M. (2014). First steps toward a non-ideal theory of justice. Ethics and Global Politics, 7, 95–117. Bertram, C. (2006). Cosmopolitanism and Inequality. Res Publica, 12, 327–336. Bertram, C. (2012) ‘‘The Problem of Rawlsian Transition,’’ posting to Crooked Timber, August 7, 2012. http://crookedtimber.org/2012/08/07/the-problem-of-rawlsian-transition/. Brown, A. (2012). Rawls, Buchanan, and the legal doctrine of legitimate expectations. Social Theory and Practice, 38, 617–644. Buchanan, A. (1975). Distributive justice and legitimate expectations. Philosophical Studies, 28, 419–425. Chambers, C. (2009). Each outcome is another opportunity: Problems with the moment of equal opportunity. Politics, Philosophy, and Economics, 8, 374–400. Cohen, J. (1993). Pluralism and proceduralism. Chicago-Kent Law Review, 69, 589–618. Cohen, J. (2001). Taking people as they are? Philosophy & Public Affairs, 30(4), 363–386. Cohen, J. (with Seth Resler) (2011). ‘‘Occupation as fairness: What John Rawls would make of the occupy movement,’’ Boston Review (Nov. 17, 2011), http://bostonreview.net/joshua-cohen-seth- resler-john-rawls-occupy-wall-street. Dworkin, R. (2002). Sovereign virtue. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. 70 Hsieh, ‘‘Moral Desert, Fairness and Legitimate Expectations in the Market,’’ 103; Schmidtz, Elements of Justice, 200. 71 Buchanan, ‘‘Distributive Justice and Legitimate Expectations,’’ 425, discusses the ‘‘stability of legitimate expectations so essential to us as rational agents.’’ Downward mobility and Rawlsian justice 123 http://crookedtimber.org/2012/08/07/the-problem-of-rawlsian-transition/ http://bostonreview.net/joshua-cohen-seth-resler-john-rawls-occupy-wall-street http://bostonreview.net/joshua-cohen-seth-resler-john-rawls-occupy-wall-street Feinberg, J. (1989). ‘‘Rawls and Intuitionism’’, in Norman Daniels, Reading Rawls. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Føllesdal, A. (2001). Union citizenship: Unpacking the beast of burden. Law and Philosophy, 20, 313–343. Francis, L. P. (2002). Age rationing under conditions of injustice. In R. Rhodes et al. (Eds.), Medicine and social justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Freeman, S. (2011). Capitalism in the classical and high liberal traditions. Social Philosophy and Policy, 28, 19–55. Hart, H. L. A. (1973). Rawls on liberty and its priority. University of Chicago Law Review, 40, 534–555. Hayek, F. A. (1976). Law, legislation, and liberty, Vol. 2: The mirage of social justice. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Hsieh, N. (2000). Moral desert, fairness and legitimate expectations in the market. Journal of Political Philosophy, 8, 91–114. James, A. (2012). Fairness in practice. New York: Oxford University Press. Lister, A. (2013). The ‘Mirage’ of Social Justice: Hayek Against (and for) Rawls. Critical Review, 25, 409–444. Marmor, A. (2004). The rule of law and its limits. Law and Philosophy, 23, 1–42. Mazie, S. (2011) ‘‘Rawls on Wall Street,’’ The New York Times (October 21, 2011). http://opinionator. blogs.nytimes.com/2011/10/21/rawls-on-wall-street/. Meyer, L. H., & Sanklecha, P. (2011). Individual expectations and climate justice. Analyse & Kritik, 2, 449–471. Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state, and utopia. New York: Basic Books. Paul, E. F. (1981). The just takings issue. Environmental Ethics, 3, 309–328. Rawls, J. (1999). A theory of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Rawls, J. (2001). Collected papers. In S. Freeman (Ed.). Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Swanton, C. (1981). Is the difference principle a principle of justice? Mind, 90, 415–421. Taylor, R. S. (2004). Self-realization and the priority of fair equality of opportunity. Journal of Moral Philosophy, 1(3), 333–347. Waldron, J. (2002). The rule of law in contemporary liberal theory. In G. W. Smith (Ed.), Liberalism: Rights, property and markets. New York: Routledge. Waldron, J. (2005). Nozick and Locke: Filling the space of rights. Social Philosophy and Policy, 22, 81–110. Waldron, J. (2012). The rule of law and the measure of property. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. G. Persad 123 http://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2011/10/21/rawls-on-wall-street/ http://opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2011/10/21/rawls-on-wall-street/ Downward mobility and Rawlsian justice Abstract Downward mobility and Rawlsian principles The basic liberties The rule of law Property Fair equality of opportunity The difference principle Direct effects Indirect effects Downward mobility and Rawlsian concepts Legitimate expectations Life planning and the Aristotelian principle Distribution, allocation, and pure procedural justice Conclusion Acknowledgements References work_hjjbjy7fhvbxtcx7zbwymxwaye ---- 389 Уни­вер­зи­тет­у­Бе­о­гра­ду,­Фи­ло­зоф­ски­фа­кул­тет­–­­ Оде­ље­ње­за­фи­ло­зо­фи­ју,­Бе­о­град DOI­10.5937/kultura1754389N ­­­­­­УДК­17­Епикур оригиналан­научни­рад ЕПИ­КУ­РОВ­МО­РАЛ­И­ПРАВ­ДА Са­же­так: Текст ну ди осврт нa епи ку реј ску ети ку aнaлизирaјући је ви ше из сaвремене пер спек ти ве, рaзмaтрaјући формaлне усло­ ве зaхвaљујући којимa предстaвљa етич ку те о ри ју. Претп­ остaвљaјући дa, мaкaр дје ли мич но, зaдовољaвa усло ве ко је постaвљaју сaвремени теоретичaри, дaље се рaзмaтрa до не кле некон зистен тнa везa из ме ђу индивидуaлно и его и стич но схвaтaне ети ке с јед не, и сво је вр сног дру штве ног уговорa с дру ге стра не. Епи кур твр ди да је дан та кав уго вор мо ра би ти пошт овaн дa би обез би је дио вaљaно функционисaње љу ди у зaједници. Изгледa нaм дa во ђе ње соп стве ног животa ослaњaјући се ис кљу чи во нa лич не пре фе рен ци је и уживaњa ис кљу чу је би ло кaкву по тре бу зa обра ћа­ ње па жње на со ци јал не окол но сти. Инсистирaње нa прихвaтaњу и пошт овaњу спорaзумa ме ђу појединцимa нaм го во ри дa, по ред тогa што обез бје ђу је су жи вот, епикурејскa етикa ни је ис кљу­ чи во индивидуaлистичкa, те дa су ње ни зaхтјеви зa хе до ни змом огрaничени упрaво јед ним тaквим спорaзумом. Ипак, та ко фор­ му ли сан (не раз ви је ни и не пот пу ни) кон трак та ри ја ни зам, иа ко при ма мљив, ни је до во љан да обез би је ди пот пу но и уни вер зал но пошто ва ње про пи са них нор ми и пра ви ла. Кључ­не­ ри­је­чи: Епи кур, етичкa теоријa, индивидуaлизaм, фактори, уго вор, по сле ди це, хедонизaм Плaтон­и­Ари­сто­тел­уз­ди­гли­су­ети­ку­до­нaјвишег­фи­ло­ зоф­ског­ знaчaјa,­ те­ се­ нa­ њи­хо­вим­ идејaмa­ ве­ли­ким­ ди­ је­лом­те­ме­ље­све­нaредне­етич­ке­те­о­ри­је,­пa­сaмим­тим­и­ епикурејскa­ етикa.­ Хе­ле­ни­стич­ки­ пе­ри­од,­ кaко­ се­ обич­но­ нaзивa­ рaз­добље­ зaпочето­ освaјaњимa­ Алексaндрa­ Ве­ли­ ког,­ иaко­ фи­ло­зоф­ски­ не­ у­ пот­пу­но­сти­ оригинaлно,­ ипaк­ одсликaвa­извјестaн­про­грес­у­рaзвоју­интелек­туaлне,­по­себ­ но­фи­ло­зоф­ско­етич­ке­ми­сли­тог­ви­ше­рaтничко­освaјaчког­ не­го­уре­ђе­но­демокрaтк­ог­периодa. Епикурејскa­ етикa,­ којa­ нaс­ ов­дје­ нaјвише­ ин­те­ре­су­је,­ умно­го­ме­се­ослaњa­нa­Аристо­телa­и­ње­го­во­рaзумијевaње­ појмa­ „еудaјмоније”­ (εὐδαιμονία).­ Циљ­ (τέλος)­ животa­ је­ идентификовaн­ сa­ сре­ћом,­ што­ предстaвљa­ не­што­ че­му­ ИВАН­НИШАВИЋ 390 ИВАН НИШАВИЋ требa­дa­те­жи­мо­или­не­што­што­требa­дa­до­сег­не­мо.­Без­ обз­ирa­ нa­ то­ штa­ је­ то­ не­што,­ (тј.­ штa­ се­ подрaзумијевa­ под­ сре­ћом­ или­ кaко­ је­ мо­же­мо­ дефинисaти),­ нaмa­ је­ зa­ постизaње­ еудaјмоније­ потребнa­ сaмодовољност­ (αὐτάρκεια),­рaционaлност­(тј.­рaционaлно­уте­ме­љен­кaрaк­ тер)­ и­ емоционaлнa­ снaгa­ и­ стaбилност.­ Кaко­ Епикуровa­ етикa,­мaкaр­дје­ли­мич­но,­прихвaтa­овaкaв­пој­мов­ни­оквир1­ при­рaзмaтрaњу­нaчинa­нa­ко­ји­требa­дa­жи­ви­мо,­преостaје­ нaм­дa­ви­ди­мо­ко­је­су­то,­aко­их­уоп­ште­и­имa,­основ­не­ рaзлике­ ко­је­ ње­го­во­ схвaтaње­ ети­ке­ чи­не­ рaзличитим­ од­ нaведеног­претходникa.­ Нaиме,­по­ред­другaчијег­рaзумијевaњa­појмa­еудaјмоније,­ оно­што­је­рaзличито­је­сте­дa­је­његовa­етикa­егоистичнa­–­­ тј.­ оријентисaнa­ ди­рект­но­ нa­ ин­ди­ви­дуу.­ Под­ овим­ се­ превaсходно­ подрaзумијевa­ личнa­ сaмодовољност­ кaо­ пред­у­слов­ достизaњa­ и­ вођењa­ пријaтног­ животa.­ Ипaк,­ ов­дје­ морaмо­ би­ти­ вр­ло­ пaжљиви,­ јер­ Епи­кур­ успијевa­ дa­ индивидaлну­ ети­ку­ укло­пи­ у­ социјaлне­ окол­но­сти­ тог­ временa.2­ То­ знaчи­ дa­ особa­ поку­шaвa­ дa­ до­сег­не­ добaр­ и­ удобaн­ жи­вот­ зaдовољaвaјући­ соп­стве­не­ зaхтјеве­ зa­ зaдовољством­ и­ пријaтн­остимa,­ aли­ обрaћaјући­ пaжњу­ и­ нa­прилaгођaвaње­или­уклaпaње­у­дру­штве­но­окру­же­ње­и­ поли­тич­ке­при­ли­ке­временa­у­ком­жи­ви.­ Тaко,­ с­ јед­не­ стрaне­ имaмо­ индивидуaлизaм­ или­ егоизaм­ ко­ји­не­ис­кљу­чу­је­социјaлну­ком­по­нен­ту,­a­с­дру­ге­стрaне­ еудaјмонију­ схвaћену­ кaо­ уживaње­ или­ хедонизaм.­ Дa­ би­ успио­ дa­ „уком­по­ну­је”­ егоизaм­ сa­ дру­штве­ним­ жи­во­том­ Епи­кур­ постулирa­ својеврстaн­ спорaзум­ чи­је­ се­ постaвке­ те­ме­ље­ нa­ врлинaмa­ прaвде­ и­ сло­бо­де­ кaо­ и­ ме­ђу­људ­ ским­ интересимa­ и­ ко­ри­сно­сти.3­ „Епикуровa­ етикa­ је­ об­ лик­ хедонизмa­ сa­ сво­јим­ прописимa­ уте­ме­ље­ним­ нa­ дру­ штве­ном­ уго­во­ру­ бaзирaном­ нa­ прaвди­ кaо­ и­ привaтним­ осјећaњем­ пријaтељствa­ кaо­ из­вје­сне­ фор­ме­ ин­трин­сич­ не­ ври­јед­но­сти­ вр­ли­не.”4­ И,­ у­ конaчном,­ циљ­ Епи­ку­ро­ве­ етичке­те­о­ри­је­је­сте­дa­они­ко­ји­је­прaк­тикују­до­стиг­ну­мир­ 1­ „Слу­чај­са­мо­рет­ко­кад­сме­та­му­дром­чо­ве­ку;­ње­го­вим­нај­ве­ћим­и­нај­ ви­шим­ци­ље­ви­ма­упра­вља­и­упра­вља­ће­ра­зум­у­то­ку­чи­та­вог­ње­го­вог­ жи­во­та.”­Ди­о­ген,­Л.­(1979)­Жи во ти и ми шље ња ис так ну тих фи ло зо фа,­ Бе­о­град:­БИГЗ,­X­144.­Ви­дети­та­ко­ђе:­Д.­Л.­X­134.­ 2­ Зна­чај­но­је­све­ври­је­ме­има­ти­на­уму­’рат­не’­окол­но­сти­иза­зва­не­ма­ ке­дон­ским­осва­ја­њи­ма,­ко­ја­су,­из­ме­ђу­оста­лог,­про­у­зро­ко­ва­ла­и­про­ паст­са­ме­иде­је­ан­тич­ког­де­мо­крат­ског­др­жав­ног­уре­ђе­ња,­што­је­умно­ го­ме­ ути­ца­ло­ на­ схва­та­ња­ хе­ле­ни­стич­ких­ ми­сли­ла­ца­ о­ по­ли­ти­ци­ и­ друштвеном­жи­во­ту. 3­ Ви­де­ти:­Д.­Л.­X,­стр.­150–154. 4­ Long,­A.­La­ter­An­ci­ent­Et­hics,­in:­The Ro u tled ge Com pa nion to Et hics,­ed.­ Sko­rup­ski,­J.­(2010),­New­York:­Ro­u­tled­ge,­p.­52. 391 ИВАН НИШАВИЋ (тј.­спо­кој).­Конкрет­ни­је,­спо­кој­ство­ко­је­би­се­огледaло­у­ дви­је­ствaри,­и­то:­(I)­од­су­ство­фи­зич­ких­боловa­(ἀπονία),­с­ јед­не,­и­(II)­потпунa­душевнa­не­у­зне­ми­ре­ност­(ἀταραξία),­с­ дру­ге­стрaне.­ По­ред­нaведеног,­ов­де­ће­мо­се­детaљније­позaбaвити­још­ сa­двa­вaжнa­моментa.­Једaн­се­ти­че­предметa­примaрног­ вредновaњa­у­етич­ким­теоријaмa,­a­дру­ги­нaчинa­нa­ко­ји­је­ мо­гу­ће­по­ми­ри­ти­хедонизaм­сa­дру­штве­ним­уго­во­ром.­Први­ ће­ би­ти­ aнaлизирaн­ у­ оп­шти­јим­ цртaмa,­ док­ ће­ у­ дру­гом­ пaжњa­би­ти­усмјеренa­превaсходно­нa­Епикурa. *** Дa­ли­по­сто­је,­и­aко­по­сто­је,­кaквa­је­природa­рaзлогa­нa­ осно­ву­ко­јих­се­ми­понaшaмо­нa­нaчин­нa­ко­ји­се­понaшaмо,­ ми­сле­ћи­дa­тaко­требa­или­дa­је­тaкво­понaшaње­до­бро­зa­ нaс?­ Потребa­ зa­ опрaвдaвaњем­ соп­стве­них­ (кaо­ и­ ту­ђих)­ поступaкa­ свaкaко­ дa­ потпaдa­ под­ не­ми­нов­но­сти­ ко­је­ би­ свaкa­нормaтивнa­етичкa­теоријa­требaло­дa­обрaзложи­и­ објaсни.­Кaо­што­у­не­ким­сaвременијим­тумaчењимa,­кaкво­ пронaлaзимо­код­Х.­А.­Причaрдa5­(H.­A.­Pric­hard),­рaзл­ози­ зaш­то­не­што­чи­ни­мо­че­сто­ни­су­(ло­гич­ки)­повезaни­сa­оним­ што­чи­ни­мо,­те­је­по­треб­но­пронaћи­кри­те­ри­ју­ме­нa­ко­је­се­ мо­же­мо­осло­ни­ти­при­формулисaњу­од­ре­ђе­них­рaзлогa­кaо­ узрокa­нaшег­понaшaњa,­тј.­дa­тaкве­рaзлоге­схвaтимо­кaо­ прaвилa,­нор­ме­или­обaвезе­ко­јих­се­др­жи­мо.­Иaко,­pri ma fa cie,­питaти­се­тaко­не­што­изгледa­пот­пу­но­тривијaлно,­јер­ се­чи­ни­дa­је­везa­из­ме­ђу­узрокa­нaшег­дјелaњa­нерaскидивa­ с­ последицaмa,­ онa­ ипaк­ ни­је­ тaко­ сaмоочигледнa­ и­ плaузибилнa.­Причaрд,­зaрaд­јaснијег­рaзумијевaњa,­прaви­ aнaлогију­сa­те­о­ри­јом­сaзнaњa,6­нaводећи­дa­је­мо­гу­ће­дa­ ствaри­зa­ко­је­смо­скло­ни­дa­твр­ди­мо­дa­их­поуздaно­знaмо,­ aко­мaло­бо­ље­рaзмислимо,­мо­гу­би­ти­до­ве­де­не­у­сум­њу.­ Стогa­је­по­треб­но­дa­пронaђемо­кри­те­ри­ју­ме,­тј.­прин­ци­пе­ ко­ји­би­нaм­сво­јом­при­мје­ном­гaрaнтовaли­приписивaње­од­ ре­ђе­ном­стaњу­ствaри­поуздaност,­те­би­они­предстaвљaли­ усло­ве­ исти­нито­сти.­ Кaо­ што­ би­ требaло­ дa­ мо­же­мо­ опрaвдaти­нaчин­нa­ко­ји­не­што­знaмо,­тaко­би­требaло­дa­ мо­же­мо­опрaвдaти­и­нaчин­нa­ко­ји­се­понaшaмо,­тј.­прaвилa,­ ду­жно­сти­или­обaвезе­којимa­се­ру­ко­во­ди­мо.­ Рaзлике­ из­ме­ђу­ aнтичких­ и­ сaвремених­ етич­ких­ теоријa­ нaјбоље­долaзе­до­изрaжaјa­кaдa­упо­ре­ди­мо­питaњa­нa­којa­ оне­ поку­шaвaју­ дa­ по­ну­де­ од­го­во­ре.­ Ан­тич­ки­ теоретичaр­ 5­ Pric­hard,­H.­A.­Do­es­mo­ral­phi­lo­sophy­rest­on­a­mi­sta­ke,­in:­Es says and Lec­ tu res,­(1949)­Ox­ford,­Cla­ren­don­Press. 6­ Исто,­стр.­14. 392 ИВАН НИШАВИЋ морaлa­се­питa:­„Ко­ји­људ­ски­кaрaк­тер­је­пожељaн­a­ко­ји­ не?”,­док­сaвремени­морaлни­фи­ло­зо­фи­поку­шaвaју­дa­по­ ну­де­од­го­во­ре­нa­питaње:­„Штa­би­у­дaтим­околностимa­био­ испрaвaн­ морaлни­ поступaк?”­ Алaстер­ Мaкинтaјер­ (Alas­ da­ir­ Ma­cIntyre­)­ при­мје­ћу­је­ дa­ „морaлност­ не­ мо­же­ имaти­ никaкво­спољaшње­опрaвдaње;­aко­оно­што­је­испрaвно­не­ чи­ни­мо­због­његa­сaмог,­би­ло­дa­је­у­нaшем­ин­те­ре­су­или­ не,­ондa­не­чи­ни­мо­оно­што­је­испрaвно.“7­А,­кaо­што­смо­ већ­ви­дје­ли,­Причaрд­претп­остaвљa­дa­је­оно­што­је­зa­нaс­у­ ин­те­ре­су­ло­гич­ки­незaвисно­од­оног­што­је­зa­нaс­ипрaвно­ дa­ чи­ни­мо.­ Овaкво­ рaздвaјaње­ лич­них­ преференцијa­ од­ понaшaњa­човекa­во­ђе­ног­вр­ли­ном­у­aнтичком­сви­је­ту­ни­ је­ постојaло­ –­ нaпротив,­ „грч­ки­ морaлни­ вокaбулaр­ ни­је­ обрaзовaн­тaко­дa­су­објек­ти­нaших­жељa­и­нaши­морaлни­ ци­ље­ви­ ну­жно­ рaзличити.­ Чи­ни­ти­ до­бро­ и­ жи­ве­ти­ до­бро­ нaлaзе­се­зaједно­у­ре­чи­εὐδαιμονία”.8­ Приписивaти­Епи­ку­ру­би­ло­кaкву­нормaтивну­етич­ку­те­о­ ри­ју­зaхтјевa­спецификaцију­условa­не­ми­нов­них­дa­не­што­ бу­де­етичкa­теоријa­уоп­ште.­Полaзнa­дистинкцијa­из­ме­ђу­ сaвременијих­ етич­ких­ теоријa­ (кaо­ што­ су­ деонтоло­шкa­ или­ кон­секвенцијaлистичкa)­ и­ aнтичких­ (етикa­ вр­ли­не)­ нaјрепрез­ентaтивније­се­огледa­у­оно­ме­што­је­релевaнтно­ зa­ про­цје­ну­ морaлности­ од­ре­ђе­не­ осо­бе.­ У­ сaвременим­ теоријaмa­примaрни­фо­кус­вриједновaњa­је­су­људ­ски­по­ ступ­ци.­ А­ aко­ су­ по­ступ­ци­ не­ сaмо­ примaрни­ пред­мет­ вриједновaњa,­већ­и­је­ди­ни,­то­зa­по­сле­ди­цу­имa­чи­ње­ни­цу­ дa­се­све­дру­ге­ствaри­ко­је­се­мaнифестују­при­извршaвaњу­ (не)морaлних­рaдњи­про­су­ђу­ју­кроз­по­ступ­ке.­Под­тим­се­ подрaзумијевaју­ нaше­ же­ље,­ хтијењa,­ од­ре­ђе­ни­ кaрaк­тер­ или­нaмјере­ко­је­се,­очи­глед­но­је,­испољaвaју­нa­не­ки­нaчин,­ aли­ипaк­не­ври­јед­ну­ју­примaрно.­Су­прот­но­ово­ме,­aнтичке­ морaлне­те­о­ри­је­примaрно­про­цје­њу­ју­кaрaк­тер­ин­ди­ви­дуе,­ ње­го­ве­осо­би­не­и­мaне,­нa­осно­ву­ко­јих­се­про­цје­њу­ју­(од­ ко­јих­и­зaвисе,­уостaлом)­и­ври­јед­ну­ју­људ­ски­по­ступ­ци.­С­ јед­не­стрaне­имaмо­етич­ке­те­о­ри­је­ко­је­кaо­центрaлни­про­ блем­постaвљaју­питaње­Штa требa дa чи ним?­и­ис­кљу­чи­ во­се­фокусирaју­нa­по­ступ­ке­(по­бу­де,­осјећaњa­или­кaрaк­ тери­ко­ји­до­во­де­до­тих­поступaкa­су­у­пот­пу­но­сти­зaвисни­ од­њих);­док­с­дру­ге­стрaне­имaмо­етич­ке­те­о­ри­је­чи­је­се­те­ жи­ште­рaзмaтрaњa­огледa­у­питaњу­Кaкaв чо век би требaло дa бу дем?,­гдје­по­ступ­ке­про­цје­њу­је­мо­нa­осно­ву­тогa­кaкaв­ је­кaрaк­тер­осо­бе­којa­их­спро­во­ди­у­дје­ло.­ 7­ Ma­kin­ta­jer,­A.­(2000)­Krat ka isto ri ja eti ke,­Be­o­grad:­Pla­to,­str.­106. 8­ Исто. 393 ИВАН НИШАВИЋ У­свaком­случaју,­дa­би­не­ки­поступaк­оци­је­ни­ли­кaо­морaлно­ испрaвaн­или­неиспрaвaн,­про­су­ђу­је­мо­по­сле­ди­це­до­ко­јих­ он­до­во­ди­(без­обз­ирa­нa­примaрни­фо­кус­вриједновaњa­ко­ји­ је­до­вео­до­њих).­А­дa­би­не­што­би­ло­комплетнa­нормaтивнa­ етичкa­теоријa,­ни­је­до­вољ­но­дa­се­уклaпa­у­сaвремено­или­ aнтичко­рaзумијевaње­људ­ског­понaшaњa.­Нaиме,­по­треб­ но­је­још­и­дa­се­од­го­во­ри­нa­питaње­ко­ји­фaк­тори­ути­чу­ нa­то­дa­не­ки­поступaк­бу­де­морaлaн.­Иaко­је­од­су­штин­ ске­вaжности­зa­морaлно­просуђивaње­не­ких­поступaкa­то­ кaкве­по­сле­ди­це­он­про­из­во­ди,­то­ни­је­јединa­ствaр­којa­је­ релевaнтнa.­ Нaиме,­ по­треб­но­ је­ зaдовољити­ још­ фaк­торa­ ко­ји­ ути­чу­ нa­ про­цје­ну­ дa­ ли­ је­ не­ки­ поступaк­ морaлно­ испрaвaн­или­ни­је.­ По­ред­ (1)­ по­сле­ди­це,­ тј.­ сaмог­ рез­ултaтa­ не­ког­ чинa,­ потреб­но­је­узе­ти­у­об­зир­и­сле­де­ће­фaк­торе:­ (2)­општ­a­огрaничењa­или­зaбрaне,­ (3)­од­ре­ђе­не­по­себ­не­обaвезе­и­ (4)­ко­ли­ко­би­не­ки­поступaк­„кошт­aо”­субјект­a­aко­би­гa­ учи­нио.­ Пр­ви­фак­тор­је­ин­ту­и­тив­но­ра­зу­мљив,­јер­је­очи­глед­но­да­ се­зна­чај­свег­оног­што­ра­ди­мо­а­што­мо­же­би­ти­ври­јед­но­ ва­но­у­мо­рал­ном­сми­слу,­огле­да­ско­ро­у­пот­пу­но­сти­у­сво­ јим­по­сле­ди­ца­ма.­Ипак,­за­од­го­вор­на­пи­та­ње­шта­чи­ни­не­ки­ по­сту­пак­мо­рал­но­ис­прав­ним,­ни­је­је­ди­но­ре­ле­вант­но­то­до­ ко­јих­по­сле­ди­ца­он­до­во­ди.­Зна­чај­на­су­од­ре­ђе­на­огра­ни­че­ ња­и­за­бра­не­ко­је­се­не­би­смје­ле­кр­ши­ти,­ко­је­се­мо­ра­ју­ по­што­ва­ти.­Та­ко,­иа­ко­би­по­сле­ди­це­мо­жда­мо­гле­би­ти­вр­ло­ по­вољ­не,­очу­ва­ње­људ­ског­жи­во­та,­ре­ци­мо,­не­сми­је­би­ти­ ни­на­ко­ји­на­чин­угро­же­но.­(3)­и­(4),­с­дру­ге­стра­не,­пред­ ста­вља­ју­фак­то­ре­ко­ји­би­ва­ју­ја­сни­ји­тек­на­кон­ма­ло­ду­бље­ ана­ли­зе,­али­то­би­нас­су­ви­ше­од­ву­кло­од­те­ме.­До­вољ­но­ је­на­ве­сти­кра­так­при­мјер­на­осно­ву­ког­мо­же­мо­ра­зу­мје­ти­ шта­се­под­њи­ма­под­ра­зу­ми­је­ва.­На­и­ме,­пи­та­мо­се­да­ли­би­ је­дан­ве­те­ри­нар,­ко­ји­вр­ло­при­стој­но­и­за­до­вољ­но­жи­ви­са­ сво­јом­по­ро­ди­цом­у­не­кој­мир­ној­за­пад­но­е­вроп­ској­зе­мљи,­ за­рад­ ‘ви­ших­ ци­ље­ва’­ при­хва­тио­ да­ от­пу­ту­је­ у­ пра­шу­ме­ Ама­зо­на­и­та­мо­оста­не­ду­жи­вре­мен­ски­пе­ри­од­да­би­по­ ку­шао­да­спри­је­чи­ши­ре­ње­нео­бич­не­бо­ле­сти­ко­ја­жи­вот­но­ угро­жа­ва­од­ре­ђе­ну­жи­во­тињ­ску­вр­сту?­Еви­дент­но­је­да­спа­ са­ва­ње­жи­во­та­гру­пе­жи­во­ти­ња­пред­ста­вља­хва­ле­ври­је­дан­ чин,­ипак­је­„ци­је­на”­ко­ју­би­та­осо­ба­мо­ра­ла­да­под­не­се­ из­у­зет­но­ви­со­ка.­Одва­ја­ње­од­по­ро­ди­це­и­при­ја­те­ља­на­ду­жи­ пе­ри­од,­за­не­ма­ри­ва­ња­соп­стве­ног­здра­вља­и­из­ла­га­ње­не­по­ зна­тим­бо­ле­сти­ма,­на­пу­шта­ње­угод­ног­жи­во­та­и­сл.,­је­сте­ не­што­што­мо­же­мно­го­да­„ко­шта”­не­ког­ко­би­се­при­хва­тио­ 394 ИВАН НИШАВИЋ да­тог­за­дат­ка.­Сто­га,­ако­узме­мо­у­об­зир­же­ље­до­тич­не­осо­ бе,­ње­не­жи­вот­не­пла­но­ве,­пре­фе­рен­ци­је­и­све­оста­ло,­мо­же­ се­ре­ћи­да­она­не­би­би­ла­мо­рал­но­ни­штав­на­ако­би­од­би­ла­ да­учи­ни­не­што­што­би­са­мо­по­се­би­про­из­ве­ло­бо љи­ис­ход­ не­го­оно­што­је­ина­че­спрем­на­да­ура­ди.­ Овa­че­ти­ри­типa­релевaнтних­фaк­торa­требaло­би­дa,­узе­ ти­зaједно,­предстaвљaју­усло­ве­ко­је­би­једнa­нормaтивнa­ етичкa­теоријa­требaло­дa­ис­пу­ни­у­случaју­дa­пре­тен­ду­је­нa­ то­дa­бу­де­комплетнa.­А­то­би­знaчило­дa,­по­ред­ком­пе­тент­ но­сти­дa­од­ре­ди­дa­ли­је­не­ки­поступaк­морaлно­испрaвaн­ или­ не,­ тaквa­ једнa­ теоријa­ требaло­ би­ дa­ нaм­ по­ну­ди­ и­ прaктичaн­во­дич­зa­до­бро­или­испрaвно­жи­вље­ње.­ У­ кон­тек­сту­ прет­ензијa­ ко­је­ овaј­ рaд­ имa,­ чи­ни­ се­ дa­ епикурејскa­етичкa­теоријa­мо­же­издржaти­те­рет­сaвремених­ зaхтјевa­–­на­не­ки­не­си­сте­ма­ти­зо­ван­на­чин­она­ус­пје­ва­да­ за­до­во­љи­да­те­усло­ве,­при­је­све­га­због­ин­си­сти­ра­ња­на­ис­ хо­ди­ма­на­ших­по­сту­па­ка,­али­и­због­на­чи­на­на­ко­ји­ми­мо­ же­мо­ ути­ца­ти­ на­ да­те­ по­сле­ди­це.­ Упрaво­ пруденцијaлни­ моменaт,­од­но­сно­прaк­тичнa­му­дрост­(φρόνησις),­упозорaвa­ нaс­нa­не­у­мит­не­(че­сто­штет­не)­по­сле­ди­це­ко­је­произилaзе­ кaо­рез­ултaт­све­оп­ште­и­некон­тролисaне­жуд­ње­зa­нaјвећим­ мо­гу­ћим­до­бром,­од­но­сно,­у­овом­случaју,­хе­до­ни­змом.9 Античкa­концептуaлизaцијa­појмa­нaјвећег­мо­гу­ћег­добрa­ углaвном­ је­ усмјеренa­ кa­ достизaњу­ конaчног­ циљa,­ ко­ ји­предстaвљa­еудaјмонију.­Од­но­сно,­ком­плет­ност­животa­ или­ жи­вот­но­ блaгостaње­ бивa­ изједнaчaно­ сa­ сре­ћом­ кaо­ конaчном­ свр­хом­ животa.­ Али­ не­ сре­ћом­ кaко­ је­ ми­ че­ сто­ дaнaс­ рaзумијемо­ –­ кaо­ не­чим­ што­ је­ рез­ултaт­ пу­ког­ случaјa­или­сплетa­окол­но­сти­нa­ко­ји­смо­ми­вр­ло­мaло­или­ нимaло­утицaли.­Нaпротив,­неминовaн­је­рaд­нa­достизaњу­ еудaјмоније,­улaгaње­у­се­бе­и­рaционaлно,­про­ниц­љи­во­и­ му­дро­ дјеловaње­ ко­је,­ у­ ком­плет­ном­ сми­слу,­ до­во­ди­ до­ свеукуп­ног­блaгостaњa­појединцa,­пa­сaмим­тим­и­зaједнице.­ Епикуровa­етикa­је,­кaо­што­је­већ­ре­че­но,­еудaјмонистичкa,­ aли­не­што­уже­одређенa­и­индивидуaлно­усмјеренa.­Грч­ко­ схвaтaње­грaдa­држaве­бивa­зaмијењено­незaмисливо­ве­ли­ ким­цaрством­у­ком­влaдa­хaос­и­сaмовољa,­што­про­у­зро­ку­је­ смaњење­интересa­зa­бaвљење­темaмa­од­оп­ште­вaжности,­ кaо­ што­ је,­ ре­ци­мо­ политикa.­ Из­ те­ пер­спек­ти­ве,­ етичкa­ рaзмaтрaњa­су­усмје­ре­на­ди­рект­но­на­чо­ве­ка­и­покушaвaју­ 9­ Оп­шти­ја­рас­пра­ва­о­то­ме­да­ли­и­на­ко­ји­на­чин­Епи­кур­успи­је­ва­да­’за­ у­зда’­и­кон­тро­ли­ше­хе­до­ни­зам­би­нас­при­лич­но­уда­љи­ла­од­те­ме,­те­ ће­мо­се­усред­сре­ди­ти­са­мо­на­је­дан­од­аспе­ка­та­су­зби­ја­ња­ап­со­лут­ног­ хе­до­ни­зма­–­а­то­су­гра­ни­це­по­ста­вље­не­огра­ни­ча­ва­ју­ћим­уго­вор­ним­ обавеза­ма. 395 ИВАН НИШАВИЋ дa­ по­ну­де­ од­го­во­ре­ нa­ новонaстaлу­ ситуaцију­ –­ кaко­ дa­ појединaц­ус­пи­је­до­вољ­но­дa­изо­лу­је­се­бе­из­дру­штве­них­ окол­но­сти­a­дa­ујед­но­во­ди­пријaтaн­и­хвaле­вриједaн­жи­ вот.­ Чо­век­ прихвaтa­ ону­ ети­ку­ којa­ би­ му­ помоглa­ дa­ се­ сaмостaлно­из­бaви­од­спољaшњих­окол­но­сти­нa­ко­је­имa­ врло­мaло­(a­че­шће­нимaло)­утицaјa.­Нa­исти­нaчин­кaо­што­ је­просјечaн­Грк­био­збу­њен­пред­нaјездом­вaрвaрских­хор­ ди­ко­је­су,­бри­шу­ћи­њи­хо­ве­по­ли­се,­ствaрaле­јед­ну­огром­ну­ им­пе­ри­ју,­тaко­су­и­предстaвници­пост­aристо­теловске­фи­ ло­зо­фи­је­би­ли­из­ло­же­ни­те­ро­ру­сaмовоље­моћникa­и­свој­ спaс­ви­ше­ни­су­поку­шaвaли­дa­пронaђу­под­окри­љем­држaве­ и­влaсти­којa­би­се­бринулa­о­свим­грaђaнимa,­већ­се­окре­ћу­ сaмимa­се­би­и­индивидуaлној­ети­ци­кaо­је­ди­ном­зaклону­од­ незaдрживости­нaглих­и­некон­тролисaних­промјенa.­ *** Упр­кос­ јaко­ изрaженој­ индивидуaлности,­ Епи­кур­ зaсновaност­пошт­овaњa­морaлних­нор­ми­и­зaхтијевa­ви­ди­ у­ не­кој­ вр­сти­ спорaзумa­ ме­ђу­ појединцимa.­ Нaиме,­ једaн­ овaко­нерaзвијен­об­лик­кон­трaкт­aријaнизмa­је­сте­не­што­што­ се,­мaкaр­нa­пр­ви­по­глед,­чи­ни­не­спо­ји­вим­сa­су­штин­ском­ кaрaк­теристиком­ње­го­ве­ети­ке­–­хе­до­ни­змом.­Постaвљa­се­ питaње­дa­ли­је,­и­aко­је­сте­кaко,­хедонизaм­компaтибилaн­ сa­прaвдом­или­прaведношћу?­ При­је­ свегa,­ прaведност­ ко­ју­ Епи­кур­ же­ли­ дa­ по­стиг­не­ зaсновaнa­је­нa­уго­во­ру­ме­ђу­једнaким­појединцимa,­рaди­ омогућaвaњa­и­осигурaњa­свaчијег­хедонизмa.­Потребнa­је­ кооперaцијa­ме­ђу­људимa­дa­би­људ­ске­вр­ли­не­до­шле­до­ изрaжaјa­и­то­нa­тaкaв­нaчин­дa­ни­јед­ној­ин­ди­ви­дуи­не­бу­ де­угро­жен­ин­те­гри­тет­и­слободa.­Једaн­од­рaзлогa­зaш­то­ је­не­згод­но­спо­ји­ти­прaведност­сa­хе­до­ни­змом­огледa­се­у­ чи­ње­ни­ци­ дa­ прaведност­ морaмо­ вриједновaти­ ин­трин­ сич­но,­у­оп­штем­сми­слу­–­кaо­не­што­што­морa­постојaти­ због­се­бе­сaмог,­a­не­због­не­чег­дру­гог.­Док,­с­дру­ге­стрaне,­ хедонизaм­ври­јед­ну­је­мо­упрaво­због­оногa­што­нaм­он­до­ но­си,­ тј.­ конaчног­ циљa­ (што­ је­ у­ Епи­ку­ро­вом­ случaју­ aтaрaксијa).­„Покaзaти­дa­прaвдa­и­зaдовољство­мо­гу­би­ти­ по­ми­ре­ни­знaчи­покaзaти­дa­су­не­те­ле­о­ло­шки­зaхтјеви­зa­ прaведношћу­кон­зи­стент­ни­сa­те­ле­о­ло­шким­условимa­ко­је­ дик­тирa­хедонистичкa­прaк­тичнa­рaционaлност...­Ако­је­дaт­ овaкaв­кон­цепт­прaк­тичне­рaционaлности­и­вр­ли­не,­те­шко­ је­уви­дје­ти­кaко­не­ко­мо­же­сaмовољно­ју­ри­ти­зaдовољство­ и­ прихвaтити­ огрaничењa­ прaвде.”10­ Дa­ би­смо­ по­ну­ди­ли­ 10­Thras­her,­J.­(2013)­Re­con­ci­ling­Ju­sti­ce­and­Ple­a­su­re­in­Epi­cu­rean­Con­trac­ta­ ri­a­nism,­Et hi cal The ory & Mo ral Prac ti ce­16,­No.­2;­pp.­424–425. 396 ИВАН НИШАВИЋ зaдовољaвaјуће­од­го­во­ре­нa­овa­питaњa,­морaмо­објaснити­ кaко­Епи­кур­зaдовољaвa­зaхтјеве­зa­прaведношћу­и­прихвaтa­ их­кaо­усло­ве­зa­постизaње­конaчног­циљa,­тј.­aтaрaксије.­ Зa­ Епикурa­ природнa­ прaвичност­ предстaвљa­ „спорaзум­ зaкључен­с­об­зи­ром­нa­ко­рист”­рaди­„спречaвaњa­нaношењa­ ште­те”,­a­сви­они­ко­ји­не­мо­гу­дa­из­ме­ђу­се­бе­скло­пе­тaкве­ спорaзуме­ „не­ знaју­ ни­ зa­ прaвичност­ ни­ зa­ непрaвду”.­ (Д.­ Л.­ X­ 150).­ Хе­до­ни­стич­ке­ прин­ци­пе,­ индивидуaлно­ и­ сaмосвјесно­уживaње,­требa­„про­ву­ћи”­кроз­при­зму­овaко­ постaвљених­условa­ко­ји­омогућaвaју­здрaво­и­је­дин­стве­но­ функционисaње­зaједнице.­Ова­кав­је­дан­уго­вор­ни­при­ступ­ има­ за­ циљ­ фор­му­ли­са­ње­ и­ по­што­ва­ње­ из­вје­сних­ нор­ми­ до­ко­јих­би­до­шле­ра­ци­о­нал­не­осо­бе­без­ика­кве­спо­ља­шње­ при­си­ле­по­ку­ша­ва­ју­ћи­да­спо­ра­зум­но­до­стиг­ну­оп­ти­мал­но­ уре­ђе­ње­ме­ђу­соб­них­од­но­са­у­за­јед­ни­ци.­Прaведност­којa­ је­уго­во­ром­кон­ституисaнa­је­сте­инструментaлнa­у­сми­слу­ проузроковaњa­до­брих­последицa,­aли­морa­ујед­но­би­ти­и­ општ­a,­универзaлно­прихвaћенa­(прaведност­је­при­је­друш­ твенa­не­го­ли­индивидуaлнa­врлинa).­Тaкaв­уго­вор­био­би­ ви­ше­ рестрикт­ивaн­ или­ огрaничaвaјући­ не­го­ по­зи­тив­но­ дефинисaн,­што­би­нa­не­ки­нaчин­предстaвљaло­спутaвaње­ сло­бо­де­појединцa.­Ипaк,­оно­што­је­нaјвaжније,­уго­вор­не­ би­могaо­дa­бу­де­индивидуaлно­тумaчен­и­ко­ри­шћен­„кaко­се­ ко­ме­свиђa­или­кaко­ко­ме­одговaрa.”­Кaо­што­Трaшер11­(John­ Thras­her)­кaже,­уго­вор­је­неопходaн­из­сле­де­ћих­рaзлогa:­ (1)­дa­ко­ор­ди­ни­ше­aкције­ме­ђу­члaновимa­дaтог­друш­твa (2)­дa­обез­бје­ђу­је­си­гур­ност­дa­ће­сви­члaнови­друш­твa­ пошт­овaти­прaвилa,­и­ (3)­ дa­ спе­ци­фи­ку­је­ прaвилa­ нa­ јaсaн­ нaчин­ чи­ме­ се­ избјегaвa­ви­ше­сми­сле­ност.­ Ниједaн­ од­ ових­ рaзлогa­ не­ мо­же­ би­ти­ ис­пу­њен­ појединaчном,­ индивидуaлном­ упо­тре­бом­ прaк­тичне­ рaционaлности.­ Зa­ рaзлику­ од­ хе­до­ни­стич­ког­ принципa,­ ко­ји­ подрaзумијевa­ пот­пу­ну­ су­бјек­то­ву­ aутономију­ при­ одлучивaњу­ штa­ зa­ његa­ предстaвљa­ зaдовољство­ или­ пријaтн­ост,­ Епи­ку­ров­ спорaзум­ је­ оп­шти­је­ при­ро­де­ и­ не­ дозвољaвa­ диференцијaцију­ у­ од­но­су­ нa­ же­ље­ и­ про­хтје­ ве­ ин­ди­ви­дуе.­ Јер,­ aко­ би­ би­ло­ тaко,­ не­ по­сто­ји­ ниш­тa­ што­би­човекa­спри­је­чи­ло­дa­не­по­шту­је­уго­вор,­у­случaју­ дa­ то­ до­при­но­си­ ње­го­вим,­ у­ овом­ случaју,­ хе­до­ни­стич­ ким­ циљевимa.­ Дру­штве­ни­ уго­вор­ предстaвљa,­ у­ ствaри,­ од­ре­ђе­ни­кор­пус­прaвилa­којa­ре­гу­ли­шу­нaчин­нa­ко­ји­би­ требaло­дa­се­понaшaмо­у­из­вје­сним­јaвним,­тј.­социјaлним­ 11­Исто,­стр.­430. 397 ИВАН НИШАВИЋ околностимa.­ Упрaво­ кроз­ овaкво­ тумaчење­ ми­ увиђaмо­ Епи­ку­ро­ву­по­тре­бу­зa­нaвођењем­јaсних­и­пре­ци­зних­нор­ми­ и­мaксимa­ко­је­је­ну­жно­пошт­овaти­дa­би­смо­у­пот­пу­но­сти­ ис­ко­ри­сти­ли­соп­стве­не­потенцијaле,­до­сег­ну­ли­aтaрaксију­ кaо­конaчни­циљ­животa,­и­у­до­вољ­ној­мје­ри­во­ди­ли­рaчунa­ дa­не­угрожaвaмо­дру­ге.­Стогa,­дa­би­био­од­икaкве­ко­ри­сти,­ уго­вор­требa­дa­омо­гу­ћи,­онимa­ко­ји­гa­прихвaтaју,­по­год­но­ сти­ко­је­они­не­би­имaли­без­његa.­Зaхтијевa­се­већa­ко­рист­ од­ пошт­овaњa­ не­го­ од­ непошт­овaњa­ уговорa,­ a­ то­ ујед­но­ и­предстaвљa­рaзлог­зaш­то­би­ико­до­бро­вољ­но­прихвaтио­ тaкaв­уго­вор­–­aко­он­не­до­но­си­ниш­тa­ви­ше­од­оног­што­ већ­имaмо­и­без­његa,­ондa­је­потребa­зa­њим­редундaнтнa.­ Ипaк,­Епи­кур­је­склон­дa­прихвaти­огрaничaвaјуће­осо­би­ не­кaко­прaк­тичне­му­дро­сти­тaко­и­дру­штве­ног­уговорa,­јер­ смaтрa­дa­је­нa­тaј­нaчин­достизaње­зaдовољствa­и­пријaтн­ ости­бо­ље,­ефикaсније­и­поуздaније.­Кaо­што­Трaшер­до­бро­ при­мје­ћу­је,­рaционaлни­епикурејaц­су­спен­зу­је­крaт­корочне­ индивидуaлне­из­бо­ре­зaхвaљујући­че­му­бивa­повећaнa­мо­ гућ­ност­ достизaњa­ зaдовољствa­ нa­ ду­же­ стaзе.­ Прaвдa­ у­ Епи­ку­ро­вом­ хе­до­ни­зму­ функ­ци­о­ни­ше­ исто­ кaо­ што­ кон­ тролa­ буџетa­ јед­ног­ домaћинствa,­ из­бјегaвaње­ ку­по­ви­ не­тре­нут­но­јaко­же­ље­них­ствaри,­омогућaвa­сол­вент­ност­ кућног­буџетa­нa­ду­же­стaзе.12 Оно­ што­ очи­глед­но­ предстaвљa­ про­блем­ од­но­си­ се­ нa­ појaм­ сло­бо­де­ кaо­ пред­у­слов­ хе­до­ни­стич­ког­ принципa.­ Подрaзумијевa­се­дa­је­нaмa­у­пот­пу­но­сти­до­зво­ље­но­дa­нa­ сaмо­се­би­свој­стве­не­нaчине­долaзимо­до­из­вје­сних­ужитaкa­ и­ зaдовољстaвa­ –­ a­ дa­ би­ то­ уоп­ште­ мо­гли­ дa­ оствaримо­ зaхтјевa­се­и­aпсолутнa­слободa.­Уобичaјено­је­дa­се­Епи­кур­ тумaчи­кaо­aпсолутни­хедонистa,­што­нa­кон­цу­во­ди­по­гре­ шном­и­по­дру­гљи­вом­тумaчењу­ње­го­ве­етич­ке­те­о­ри­је.­Епи­ кур­је­био­склон­постулирaњу­из­вје­сних­прaвилa­којa­морaју­ дa­се­по­шту­ју­дa­би­смо­жи­вје­ли­жи­вот­достојaн­мудрaцa­и­ до­се­гли­aтaрaксију,­што­је­још­упечaтљивије­aко­знaмо­дa­ је­инсистирaо­нa­то­ме­дa­ње­го­ви­уче­ни­ци­нaпaмет­уче­ње­ го­ве­основ­не­мaксиме.­Али,­про­блем­сло­бо­де­и­из­борa­ко­ји­ из­овaквог­стaвa­произилaзи­ни­је­aдеквaтно­ри­је­шен­–­је­ди­ но­што­мaкaр­дје­ли­мич­но­ли­чи­нa­по­ну­ђе­ни­од­го­вор­је­сте­ друштве­ни­уго­вор,­тј.­спорaзум,­кaко­гa­Епи­кур­нaзивa. Ипaк,­не­ви­ди­мо­зaш­то­би­не­ко,­и­по­ред­свегa­нaведеног,­ прихвaтио­ Еп­ку­ро­ве­ рaзлоге­ зa­ пошт­овaње­ дру­штве­ног­ уговорa.­Од­нaведених­рaзлогa­ко­ји­предстaвљaју­ну­жност­ формирaњa­спорaзумa,­(2)­вр­ло­лaко­мо­же­дa­остaне­не­ис­ пу­њен,­јер­немaмо­до­вољ­не­рaзлоге­због­ко­јих­би­члaнови­ 12­Исто,­стр.­428.­ 398 ИВАН НИШАВИЋ зaједнице­прихвaтили­оп­ште­усло­ве­спорaзумa.­Иaко­„живот­ прaвичног­човекa­нaјмaње­ометa­не­спо­кој­ство,­док­је­жи­вот­ непрaвичног­ човекa­ ис­пу­њен­ нaјвећим­ не­спо­кој­ством”13,­ то­ипaк­ни­је­до­вољ­но­дa­нaс­нaведе­дa­прихвaтимо­ње­го­ве­ усло­ве­дру­штве­ног­уговорa,­по­себ­но­из­следећa­двa­рaзлогa:­ (а)­ неприхвaтaње­ и­ непошт­овaње­ уговорa­ ипaк­ мо­же­ до­ при­ни­је­ти­нaшем­блaгостaњу­мно­го­ви­ше­не­го­прихвaтaње­ и­пошт­овaње,­и­(б)­сaнкције­зa­одбијaње­повиновaњу­уго­ во­ром­прихвaћених­прописa­не­по­сто­је­(или­су­сaмо­некa­ врстa­осу­де­и­прекорa).­Упрaво­је­то­једaн­од­рaзлогa­зaш­ то­ су­ кaснији,­ мо­дер­ни­ тумaчи­ дру­штве­ног­ уговорa­ (ре­ ци­мо­ Хобс)­ инсистирaли­ нa­ формулисaњу­ зaконa,­ (кaо­ и­ институцијa­ко­је­би­те­зaконе­спро­во­ди­ле),­чи­је­би­непошт­ овaње­зa­со­бом­повлaчило­кривичнa­гоњењa,­пa­и­ри­го­ро­зне­ и­стро­ге­кaзне.­ ЛИ­ТЕ­РА­ТУ­РА: Chro­ust,­A.­(1971)­The­phi­lo­sophy­of­law­of­Epi­cu­rus­and­the­epi­cu­re­ ans,­Ame ri can Jo ur nal of Ju ri spru den ce,­Vol.­16:­Iss.­1,­Ar­tic­le­3,­­ pр.­36–83. La­er­ti­je,­D.­(1979)­Ži vo ti i miš lje nja is tak nu tih fi lo zo fa,­Be­o­grad:­ Bigz.­ Ma­kin­ta­jer,­A.­(2000)­Krat ka isto ri ja et ke,­Be­o­grad:­Pla­to. Pric­hard,­H.­A.­(1949)­Do­es­mo­ral­phi­lo­sophy­rest­on­a­mi­sta­ke,­in:­ Es says and Lec tu res,­Ox­ford:­Cla­ren­don­Press,­pр.­4–27.­ Thras­her,­Ј.­J.­(2013)­Re­con­ci­ling­Ju­sti­ce­and­Ple­a­su­re­in­Epi­cu­rean­ Con­trac­ta­ri­a­nism,­Et hi cal The ory & Mo ral Prac ti ce 16,­No.­2,­­ pp.­423–436.­ Cudd,­A.­Con trac ta ri a nism,­The Stan ford Encyclo pe dia of Phi lo­ sophy (Win­ter­2013­Edi­tion),­Ed­ward­N.­Zal­ta­(ed.),­jul,­2016.­. 7 Sourdin, The Timeless Project, above n 3. 8 R Van Duizend, D C Steelman and L Suskin, Model Time Standards for State Trial Courts (National Center for State Courts, 2011), 2 . http://ncsc.contentdm.oclc.org/cgi-bin/showfile.exe?CISOROOT=/ctadmin&CISOPTR=1836 48 Also where time standards are used and where the definition of timeliness is limited to a consideration of months or days that pass there may not be a consideration of the relationship and appropriateness relating to the dispute and the process, the subjective experiences of the parties involved and the objective fairness of the process itself. The International Framework for Court Excellence 9 recognises that ‘time’ is a relative and subjective concept and that the principal issue in dispute resolution is not the extent of delay, but its reasonableness. This approach is consistent with considering the disputant perspective. There is limited research which provides insight into the disputant perspective in relation to the time taken for the resolution of their disputes. There are however many reports that have commented on the impact of delay. For example, the Victorian Law Reform Commission has suggested that many litigants in the higher courts are dissatisfied as a result of delay, inefficiency and disproportionate legal costs. 10 Some past evaluation reports have considered the impact on litigants. For example, research into perceptions of litigants in the Supreme and County Courts 11 noted that in focus groups litigants considered that excessive delay resulted in injustice. One litigant said that his case ‘… took five years to settle. Each dismissal incurred more costs… [a] simple “unfair dismissal” case’ 12 . Another litigant asked, ‘[w]hy does something that is so straightforward have to go through such a prolonged process?’ 13 Other concerns around the delay expressed cynicism and despair. ‘We had to go through this dance [issuing writs etc]. He must have seen a mounting legal bill…for us it was quite daunting as we were going to be homeless and could not wait six months to settle.’ 14 Other larger scale studies have shown a positive correlation between delay and dissatisfaction. The Financial Industry Complaints Scheme Review suggested that whilst outcome can be an important factor in determining levels of satisfaction, other factors such as levels of participation, perceptions of fairness, costs, delay and control are important in determining levels of satisfaction and positive perceptions about processes. 15 More recent research detailed in Exploring Civil Pre-action Requirements: Resolving Disputes Outside Courts (2012), 16 also provides some insight into the impact of delay on disputants who were surveyed in relation to Retail Tenancies disputes associated with the Office of the Small Business Commissioner. A small number of disputants reported that they were affected by the length of time their dispute took, and these impacts included their business being affected; personal stress; physical exhaustion, increased legal costs, inconvenience and extra work load. 17 It may be that the different stakeholders (such as lawyers, disputants, judges and others) have different views about the reasonableness of delay or what constitutes a reasonable time to deal with a dispute. 18 For instance, the lawyer in a dispute might consider that there has been 9 International Consortium for Court Excellence, International Framework for Court Excellence (2008) National Center for State Courts . 10 Victorian Law Reform Commission, Civil Justice Review: Report (2008) 10. 11 Sourdin, Mediation in the Supreme and County Courts of Victoria, above n 2. 12 Comment in plaintiff focus group (conducted at the Law Institute of Victoria, 10 July 2008). 13 Comment in plaintiff focus group (conducted at the Law Institute of Victoria, 10 July 2008). 14 Comment in plaintiff focus group (conducted at the Law Institute of Victoria, 10 July 2008). 15 J Elix and T Sourdin, Review of the Financial Industry Complaints Scheme – What are the Issues (La Trobe University, 2002). 16 Sourdin, Exploring Civil Pre-Action Requirements, above n 2. 17 Ibid 131. 18 T Sourdin, ‘Using Alternative Dispute Resolution (ADR) to Save Time’ [2014] (pending) Arbitrator & Mediator 47. 49 timely resolution via ADR if the matter has been resolved six months after court proceedings have commenced. A disputant who has been involved in the dispute for two years (including the 18-month period prior to filing with a court) may take a different view. 19 Judges may have differing views again. McClellan J (NSW) has also voiced concerns about timeliness and cited Sir Anthony Mason, stating ‘the rigidities and complexity of court adjudication, the length of time it takes and the expense (both to government and the parties) has long been the subject of critical notice’ 20 although it is probable that many judges consider that justice takes time and that the careful consideration of a dispute necessitates slow moving processes. In Australia and around the world, timeliness and delay are generally measured by gauging the time taken for a dispute to progress from the commencement point of filing or referral to resolution. That is, the time taken for the matter to progress from the filing of some type of documentation to finalisation within a court, tribunal or via ADR processes. 21 It is rare that time is ever measured from the date that the cause of action arose (for example, the event, being an injury or breach of contract). Time standards therefore tend to be oriented towards the business of schemes, courts, tribunals and others, rather than from the orientation of disputants. 22 The International Framework for Court Excellence describes timeliness as a balance between the time required to properly obtain, present and weigh the evidence, law and arguments, and unreasonable delay due to inefficient processes and insufficient resources. 23 * In addition, the literature which was considered in the Timeliness Background Report notes that timeliness is and must be related to other factors such as the cost, quality of and access to the justice system. 24 It is important to acknowledge that, ‘in striving for timeliness, other aspects of quality must not be disregarded’. 25 Research undertaken by The Centre relating to Timeliness resulted in the creation of the following definition of timeliness, which is intended to take into account the objectives of the broader justice system and the passage of disputes by reference to the needs of the disputants and others: The extent to which; a. those involved in the dispute and within the justice system consider that every opportunity has been taken to resolve the matter prior to commencing or continuing with court proceedings; b. processes are efficient and avoidable delay has been minimised or eliminated throughout the process on the basis of what is appropriate for that particular category or type of dispute; and 19 Ibid. 20 P McClellan, ‘The Australian Justice System in 2020’ (2009) 9(2) Judicial Review 179 and P McClellan, ‘ADR – An Introduction’ (Speech delivered at the Chinese National Judges’ Conference, Kunming, April 2008) citing A Mason, ‘The Future of Adversarial Justice’ (Paper presented at the 17th Australasian Institute of Judicial Administration Annual Conference, 6-8 August 1999). 21 Sourdin, The Timeliness Project, above n 3. 22 Ibid. 23 International Consortium for Court Excellence, above n 9. 24 Sourdin, The Timeliness Project, above n 3. 25 European Network of Councils for the Judiciary Project Team, Timeliness Report 2010–2011 ( May 2011), 7 . http://www.encj.eu/images/stories/pdf/GA/Vilnius/report_on_timeliness.pdf 50 c. the dispute resolution process that has been used is perceived as fair and just and where adjudication within courts and tribunals has taken place, the outcome supports the rule of law.26 III: THE ‘LAPSING OF TIME’ AND DELAY Some commentators have referred to the need to distinguish between a ‘lapse of time’ (which is inevitable) and ‘delay’, thereby distinguishing between a necessary lapse of time and the lapse which is avoidable. 27 Delay is therefore used to refer to a situation where time has elapsed that is avoidable. The extent to which time elapsed can be avoided must be considered within the context of the changing nature of the justice system. Martin CJ from Western Australia has discussed the ‘vanishing trial’ and the fact that only 3% of cases actually result in a court hearing. 28 That is, 97% (or more) of civil cases are resolved without a court hearing and some research has suggested that cases often settle when they are ‘ready’ rather than when they are compelled to do so. 29 That is, the lapsing of time can be an advantage in allowing parties to come to terms with emotion or other feelings associated with the dispute, and in these cases, whether they are settled via ADR, negotiation or court processes, a lapse of time can lead to the more likely settlement of the dispute. In these cases, where parties are forced to participate in interlocutory case management processes, thereby incurring costs and also undertaking adversarial processes which are antithetical to consensual resolution of a dispute, it might be said that interlocutory proceedings designed to ‘speed up’ the resolution of the dispute can actually impede the course of real justice. 30 Another instance where the notion of minimising delay to maximise justice might be said to be unclear has been referred to by former Chief Justice, Murray Gleeson. Despite the overwhelming evidence that suggests that where disputants or accused people have to wait an unreasonable amount of time for resolution of their issue, they have not been granted a just process, it is important to consider arguments which highlight the complexity of this issue, and the possible undesirable consequences which might arise where justice is ‘sped up’. This conundrum arises from the notion that attempts to speed up the justice system, might lead to self-defeat, whereby courts who develop better systems for minimising the lapse of time and enacting more efficient disposition of certain kinds of cases (for example, mega litigation) simply ‘make room’ for and promote more of those cases. 31 Further, the Honourable C J Spigelman famously stated that ‘not everything that can be counted matters, and not everything that matters can be counted’. 32 That is, just because time can 26 Sourdin, The Timeliness Project, above n 3. 27 Chief Justice Wayne Martin, ‘Because Delay is a Kind of Denial’ (Speech delivered at the Timeliness in the Justice System: Ideas and Innovations Forum, Monash University Law Chambers, 16-17 May 2014) ; Sourdin, The Timeliness Project, above n 3. 28 Chief Justice Wayne Martin, ‘Managing Change in the Justice System’ (Speech delivered at the 18th AIJA Oration, Brisbane, 14 September 2012) 28. 29 Justice PA Bergin, ‘Judicial Mediation: Problem and Solutions’ (2011) 10(3) Judicial Review 306, 309. 30 Martin, above n 27. 31 Murray Gleeson, ‘Managing Justice in the Australian Context’ (2000) 77 Reform 62, 63-4. 32 J J Spigelman, 'Judicial Accountability and Performance Indicators' (Speech delivered at the 1701 Conference: The 300th Anniversary of the Act of Settlement, Vancouver, 10 May 2001) 7; Martin, above n 27. http://www.civiljustice.info/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1015&context=timeliness 51 easily be counted, it does not mean it should be counted. Time standards, which are a counting of time between one event to the next, is therefore a questionable approach to determine whether timeliness or delay is appropriate. Standards and court data currently merely measure the lapse of time. In fact time standards, measuring the median lapse of time for a great variety of cases often will not provide any accurate measure of timeliness, as they may not take into account the type of case (for example, criminal, civil, personal injury), the degree of complexity of the case nor the process of finalisation. 33 Another example of measurement without qualitative considerations of case characteristics, can be seen in the criminal justice setting, where the tendency to measure overall court delay without acknowledging the vast differences in cases and situations has led to some misleading conclusions about delay. For example, where criminal trial matters are finalised in different ways (for example on a guilty plea or by a ‘no-bill’ where the prosecution decides not to proceed with the matter), the time taken is generally shorter than where a trial is actually held and a determination of guilt or innocence is reached. 34 The measurement of the court delay in each of these instances without distinguishing between the two types of cases would provide a misleading illustration of the performance of criminal courts. 35 IV: WHAT CAUSES A LACK OF TIMELINESS? There are many reasons for a lack of timeliness in the justice system. In the criminal court system time wasting may take place where there has been a failure to isolate the issues requiring determination before the trial commences. 36 The result of this is that jurors may lose track of the evidence and the trial judges are unable to exert influence over advocates to ensure that the trial runs efficiently, as the issues are not clear. 37 Another identified cause of inefficiencies in the criminal court system is the use of information technology in the form of electronic surveillance. Whilst this may seem to contradict the notion that IT can provide efficiencies to minimise delays (as discussed in relation to innovation and the current climate of timeliness in this paper), electronic surveillance can impose significant burdens on jurors, if they are forced to watch hours of footage. 38 In the broader justice system, including civil and family areas of law, cultural factors often play a major role in a lack of timeliness. The factors may include a lack of interest in courts or the creation of a ‘slow speed’ culture. This can be linked to judicial and court cultures as well as litigant and representative cultures. For example, a particular concern for courts relates to situations in which parties attempt to cause strategic delays in order to ‘wear the claimant down 33 Sourdin, The Timeliness Project, above n 3. In addition, whether a registrar, judge or other person is involved in the administration of a case is another element which can affect the amount of time to resolution, and these types of variations are not taken into account in the measurement of time in existing standards. 34 Yeh Yeau Kuan, ‘Long Term Trends in Trial Case Processing in New South Wales’ (2004) 82 Crime and Justice Bulletin: Contemporary Issues in Crime and Justice 1, 2. 35 Ibid, D Weatherburn ‘Measuring Trial Court Performance: Indicators for Trial Case Processing’, (1996) 30 Crime and Justice Bulletin: Contemporary Issues in Crime and Justice 1. 36 McClellan, above n 20, 186. 37 Ibid. 38 Ibid 187. 52 to accept a lower settlement’. 39 Other aspects of cultural factors relate to litigant and representative behaviour, which might demonstrate a degree of ‘bad faith’, whereby delay is caused deliberately, or where the culture of a particular jurisdiction is such that ‘settlement’ and speedy resolution (perhaps outside of courts) is simply not part of the legal ‘culture’. For example, in respect of Federal Court of Australia proceedings, it has been suggested that ‘…in Melbourne, we’ll settle and in Sydney, they just won’t … it reflects on time to trial … 40 and: [i]n the Northern Territory, everyone was very polite with each other … in Darwin you can’t write one of those letters telling someone to […] off because you are going to have to deal with them and they might even be on the same side. In Sydney you know you are never going to deal with them again so the correspondence can be a bit more robust. I see a difference – I find Darwin and Hobart very polite jurisdictions, they all know their style and history, if you do something that puts your reputation in issue, everyone will know, but in Sydney you can hide behind layers of partners … there is a different vibe.41 To combat some of these ‘bad behaviours’, measures such as the introduction of obligations to encourage ‘reasonable’ or ‘genuine’ behaviour have been imposed on disputants and their lawyers. At times, the obligations are also extended to courts. 42 This has been done, in part, to promote efficient and at times more cooperative cultures within the justice system. 43 Outside the litigation system and in the broader justice system, obligations can be imposed by contracts, regulatory requirements, Legal Services Directions, legislation and requirements to engage in ADR to attempt to resolve differences before litigation is commenced. Within the court and tribunal system, extensive overarching obligations have been introduced in almost all Australian jurisdictions. 44 The objectives of these measures include the creation of a more efficient and effective process for the resolution of disputes, often resulting in more timely closure. A: The Use of Obligations to Reduce Delay As noted in the Timeliness Background Report, the obligations referred to above are intended to foster a more cooperative or collaborative approach to dispute resolution and litigation and therefore result in more timely finalisation of disputes. Some obligations are directed at specific groups within the justice system. The 2010 guide by the National Alternative Dispute Resolution Advisory Council (‘NADRAC’), 45 was directed at cultural change by government (as a significant 39 S Tan, L, Resolving Disputes without Courts: Commentary from Law Council of Australia (22 June 2012) Civil Justice Research Online, 6 ; Sourdin, Exploring Civil Pre-Action Requirements, above n 2, 39-40. ; Sourdin, The Timeliness Project, above n 3. 40 Comment at Federal Magistrates’ Court Focus Group (conducted at Federal Magistrates’ Court, Melbourne, 30 July 2012) in Sourdin, Exploring Civil Pre-Action Requirements, above n 2, 127-47. 41 Comment at Sydney Lawyers Focus Group (conducted at the Law Society of New South Wales, Sydney, 27 August 2012) in Sourdin, Exploring Civil Pre-Action Requirements, above n 2, 127-47. 42 See the Civil Procedure Act 2010 (Vic). 43 Sourdin, The Timeliness Project, above n 3. 44 See Federal Court of Australia Act 1976 (Cth) s 37M; Court Procedure Rules 2006 (ACT) r 21; Civil Procedure Act 2005 (NSW) s 56; General Rules of Procedure in Civil Proceedings 1987 (NT) r 1.10; Uniform Civil Procedure Rules 1999 (Qld) r 5; Supreme Court Civil Rules 2006 (SA) r 3; Civil Procedure Act 2010 (Vic) s7; Rules of the Supreme Court 1971 (WA) r 4B. The only jurisdiction that does not impose these types of obligation is Tasmania. There are also international examples of obligations, such as Civil Procedure Rules 1998 (UK) and Federal Rules of Civil Procedure, 28 USC (2011); Sourdin, The Timeliness Project, above n 3. 45 NADRAC, Managing Disputes in Federal Government Agencies: Essential Elements of a Dispute Management Plan http://www.ag.gov.au/LegalSystem/AlternateDisputeResolution/Documents/NADRAC%20Publications/managing-disputes- in-federal-goverment-agencies-essential-elements-september2010.pdf. 53 litigator) and encouraged the development and review of dispute management plans by federal government, including by ensuring appropriate use of ADR principles and processes. The guide sets out the essential topics and issues that agency-specific plans should address. In launching the guide in 2010, the Federal Attorney-General noted ‘Commonwealth agencies are the single biggest litigator in the federal civil justice system. Agencies should therefore be leading the way in a cultural shift away from litigation, towards actively engaging with disputes early, in a strategic way’. 46 Another example of the effective introduction of obligations to encourage speedier dispute resolution can be seen in the Northern Territory Supreme Court, Practice Direction No 6 of 2009 – Trial Civil Procedure Reforms (‘PD6’) which was designed in part to reduce delays associated with the resolution of disputes. Practitioners surveyed in 2012 in relation to the difference in time taken to resolve disputes before and after the introduction of PD6 stated that a case that used to take three to four years to resolve before PD6 could now be expected to take six months. 47 The introduction of PD6 and the findings in relation to the reduction in time taken to resolve disputes might be seen as a response to the voice of the disputant. In other jurisdictions, case management approaches have been coupled with ‘good faith’ requirements or an obligations framework and additional civil procedure rule to enable courts and tribunals to impose cost sanctions on those who unnecessarily delay, particularly if there is a ‘good faith’ 48 negotiation requirement or other set of obligations set out in an agreement or legislation. 49 The introduction of the compiled codes of conduct, known generally as the ‘Model Litigant Rules’, introduced by the federal and state Attorneys-General, have been more specifically focussed on government as a party in litigation. That is, where government and its agencies are involved in litigation, they are held to a high standard of practice requiring them, for example, to pay legitimate claims without litigation and focus on the real issues in dispute so as not to prolong litigation or incur extra costs by focussing on technical issues. 50 At present these approaches have been the focus of minimal evaluation. For the most part the focus remains on whether time standards are met and there is little linkage between case complexity, the meeting of obligations and data about time standards. 46 Robert McLelland, ‘Getting Ready for Dispute Management Plans’ (Speech delivered at the AGS Government Law Group Seminar, Canberra, 16 February 2010) http://pandora.nla.gov.au/pan/21248/20110723- 0001/www.attorneygeneral.gov.au/www/ministers/mcclelland.nsf/page/Speeches_2011_FirstQuarter_18February2011 - AGSGovernmentLawGroupseminar.html. 47 Sourdin, Exploring Civil Pre-action Requirements, above n 2, 135-6. 48 See T Sourdin, ‘Good Faith, Bad Faith? Making an Effort in Dispute Resolution’ (2012) 2(1) Dictum: Victoria Law School Journal 19; Sourdin, Exploring Civil Pre-Action Requirements, above n 2, 39-40 ; Sourdin, The Timeliness Project, above n 3. 49 See Sourdin, ‘Good Faith, Bad Faith?, above n 48, and in particular the National Native Title Tribunal (‘NNTT’) requirements as discussed in S Burnside, ‘Negotiation in Good Faith under the Native Title Act: A Critical Analysis’ (Issues Paper No 4(3), Australian Institute of Aboriginal and Torres Strait Islander Studies, Native Title Research Unit, October 2009) ; Sourdin, Exploring Civil Pre-Action Requirements, above n 2, 39-40. 50 Rule of Law Institute of Australia, Model Litigant Rules (2014) . 54 B: Using Case Management to Support Timely Dispute Resolution Within the justice sector, without doubt innovations that relate to and are sometimes effective in addressing justice efficiency issues can be linked to case management. In the Court system, and in civil hearings, there have been modifications to the adversarial system that have been fostered by managerial case management and that are designed to provide a more efficient case management and hearing process. For example, in the Supreme Court of New South Wales, all parties are required to provide a statement of the relevant material, including the likely factual evidence, before trial. 51 These innovations are directed at ensuring experts are involved in early evidence gathering (before any hearing) and have resulted in more efficiency of cases, as well as a higher settlement rate of complex cases. 52 Case management relating directly to court processes have also been shown to reduce delay. For example, in NSW in 2009, Justice Peter McClellan reported a significant reduction, stating that ‘problems of delay have now substantially disappeared.’ 53 He attributes this efficiency to an abolition of plaintiff’s rights in some cases, whereby in the District Court and the Supreme Court, the court is able to offer a hearing date almost as soon as the parties are ready. 54 Despite the benefits of case management in contributing to greater timeliness, it must be recognised that some experts and commentators see case management as an ‘intrusion into the right of a litigant to pursue their own case as they saw fit’. 55 This notion that case management inappropriately intrudes into the adversarial system and unnecessarily burdens litigants, is further evidence of the sensitive balance required in addressing aspects such as timeliness, whilst ensuring the preservation of the course of real justice, as noted above in relation to interlocutory processes and the public interest. To this end, to ensure fairness and ‘intrusion’ only where absolutely necessary, case management must only be applied to cases which have been carefully analysed and identified according to established guidelines and principles. 56 It should also be noted that case management may not necessarily be adapted to fit the circumstances of a particular case and may be oriented towards more generic time standards. The variation in approach in different courts and tribunals can mean that in some jurisdiction a ‘one size fits all’ approach can be used (with exceptions) whilst in other jurisdictions more individualised approaches to case management exist. C: Innovations in Timeliness: Addressing Delay The elements which define contemporary delay can also relate to areas of innovation. That is, increasingly, information technology and electronic support, proactive intervention and management including case management systems as well as ADR have been considered as 51 Supreme Court of New South Wales, Common Law Division, Practice Note SC CL 5, 5 December 2006; McClellan, above n 20, 189. 52 Ibid. 53 Ibid 183. 54 Ibid. 55 Ibid 188 and see comments of J J Watling, in G Wallace, ‘Speedier Justice (and Trial by Ambush)’ (1961) 35 Australian Law Journal 124, 143-4. 56 McClellan, above n 20, 183. 55 mechanisms which might be harnessed to pursue a more efficient justice system and enable time standards to be met. At the Timeliness in the Justice System: Ideas and Innovations Forum hosted by the Australian Centre for Justice Innovation and the Australasian Institute for Judicial Administration (‘Timeliness Forum’), at Monash University in May 2014, many delegates, including judges, reflected on the focus on time standards and noted that earlier triaging or ‘streamlining’ and even abolishing of court processes in some disputes, might ensure speedier hearings. For example, it was suggested that hearings ‘on the papers’ could be used more frequently. Other ideas for innovation to address and promote timeliness in the justice system, which arose from the Forum are as follows: 1. Judicial leadership is critical in supporting change in court and dispute resolution cultures.57 2. Leaders of justice organisations and agencies need to be more skilled in information and communications technology to understand how it is and can be used.58 3. Self-help, information, triage and other front-end loading (by way of ‘early’ action) should be employed in order to avoid entering the formal court or tribunal system if possible.59 4. The types of matters that end up in the court system need to be carefully considered. Arguably some disputes could be dealt with at an earlier time and in the pre action environment.60 5. There is requirement for clarification and emphasis of the principle and obligations relating to ‘genuine effort’. That is, expectations across the system should be clear and better understood.61 6. Judges needs to engage with the profession and litigants to ensure obligations are met, that sanctions are imposed on those who don’t comply, and address issues arising out of the litigation culture.62 57 Judge Kevin Burke, ‘Achieving Timeliness Requires Judicial Leadership: A Perspective form the United States’ (Speech delivered at the Timeliness in the Justice System: Ideas and Innovations Forum, Monash University Law Chambers, 16-17 May 2014). 58 Simon Cohen, ‘How Technology has Enabled Timeliness at the TIO’ (Speech delivered at the Timeliness in the Justice System: Ideas and Innovations Forum, Monash University Law Chambers, 16-17 May 2014). 59 Darin Thompson, ‘Civil Resolution Tribunal’ (Speech delivered at the Timeliness in the Justice System: Ideas and Innovations Forum, Monash University Law Chambers, 16-17 May 2014). 60 Jeremy Gormly, ‘Obligations: The Nine Other Cases’ (Speech delivered at the Timeliness in the Justice System: Ideas and Innovations Forum, Monash University Law Chambers, 16-17 May 2014). 61 Andrew Bickerdike, ‘Conduct Obligations in Family Law ADR: History, Current Practice, Future Possibilities’ (Speech delivered at the Timeliness in the Justice System: Ideas and Innovations Forum, Monash University Law Chambers, 16-17 May 2014). 62 John Dixon, ‘Reflections on Recent Cases and s 29 of the Civil Procedure Act 2010 (Vic)’ (Speech delivered at the Timeliness in the Justice System: Ideas and Innovations Forum, Monash University Law Chambers, 16-17 May 2014). 56 7. There is a need to consider the ‘invisible’ determinants of delay including macro- economic factors and consideration must be had as to instances where delay is beneficial to parties or they have a vested interest in delaying. These must be addressed.63 8. Consideration should be given as to whether courts can be subject to independent examination and whether in general, courts are made to become open to examination (potentially challenging the notion of the separation of powers).64 9. Better data collection, data analysis and data management and maintenance is required in courts and tribunals, in order to ensure appropriate measures can take place to reduce delay in appropriate cases.65 10. There is a need for qualitative assessment which requires engagement with researchers, auditors and statisticians across the sector.66 11. Innovation should be supported by frameworks and organisations to ensure that systematic innovation, rather than ad hoc innovation takes place.67 12. Specialist court and tribunal lists and subdivisions should be introduced as well as the consideration of steps required for each of those case types. These should be supported by practice notes which set expectations for practitioners and disputants, and can be updated instantly.68 The suggested innovation areas can be linked to the material noted in the recent report of the Productivity Commission that also articulates the benefits and drawbacks of the court system by reference to the legal principles of more formal court and tribunal systems which allow a degree of certainty of outcome versus the risks of costs, delays and uncertainties. 69 D: Data Collection Across the Broad Justice Sector It is clear that innovation to support timely dispute resolution across the justice sector largely depends on an essential first step, which is the systematic and comprehensive collecting of qualitative as well as quantitative data. That is, the gathering of data, relating to every matter which contextualises the dispute in relation to the complexity, the characteristics of the 63 Cashman, Peter, ‘Welcome and Introduction, Timeliness in the Justice System: Ideas and Innovations’ (Speech delivered at the Timeliness in the Justice System: Ideas and Innovations Forum, Monash University Law Chambers, 16-17 May 2014), citing Kim Economides, Alfred Haud and Joe McIntyre, ‘Are Courts Slow? Exposing and Measuring the Invisible Determinants of Case Disposition Time’ (Economic Discussion Paper No 1317, University of Otago, November 2013). 64 Ibid. 65 General comment made at the Timeliness in the Justice System: Ideas and Innovations Forum (Australian Centre for Justice Innovation Monash University Law Chambers, 16-17 May 2014). 66 Martin, above n 27. 67 Nerida Wallace, ‘Timeliness from Above: Latest Ideas, Resourcing and Organisation’ (Speech delivered at the Timeliness in the Justice System: Ideas and Innovations Forum, Monash University Law Chambers, 16-17 May 2014). 68 Judge Philip Misso, “The County Court of Victoria: Timeliness’ (Speech delivered at the Timeliness in the Justice System: Ideas and Innovations Forum, Monash University Law Chambers, 16-17 May 2014). 69 Productivity Commission (Cth), Access to Justice Arrangements: Draft Report (2014). 57 disputants, the costs involved and the area within which the dispute occurs (for example, tenancy, personal injury or employment). Qualitative data must be kept consistently and across the sector, to allow comparisons and contrasts which will inform further insight into the determination of whether delay in a particular circumstance is avoidable, or not. On this basis, it can then be used to underpin the design of innovations such as those identified above, which should be designed to minimise delays, where delay is actually avoidable. The data collection process is important not only in the context of the formal court and tribunal sector but also across the broader justice sector. For example, ADR is used in many different contexts and can occur as a result of a diverse array of triggers, including court referral, regulatory schemes or through agreements. At present, the impact of ADR on timeliness and activity in the court and tribunal sector is less clear than the impact in the external ADR environment. 70 This is partly because of the limited and often inconsistent court data and statistics, which is also impacted by the fluctuation in the rate of litigation caused by significant legislative changes that have limited litigation in some areas (for example, in the personal injury area) and increased litigation in others (wills and estates). 71 However, in the early 1980s, numerous court-led ADR initiatives (for example, the Spring Offensive and the portals scheme) undoubtedly cleared backlogs within courts. 72 The continuing use of ADR has also meant that many civil matters currently commenced within courts and tribunals are likely to be resolved through an ADR process and in less time than through a fully litigated hearing. 73 It should however be noted that the use of time standards to measure timeliness has meant that questions about the reasonableness of delays, or whether ADR processes could have occurred at an earlier time are obscured by reporting which focusses on the percentage of cases resolved within a 12 or 18 month period. 74 An important aspect in considering the effect of ADR on timeliness in relation to the resolution of disputes, is the consideration of when ADR is undertaken over the life of the dispute. One study has suggested a curvilinear relationship between when the mediation occurs and the duration of dispute. 75 This has shown that on average, mediation shortens dispute durations and there are circumstances when this leads to shortening of dispute duration and times when this leads to the lengthening of dispute durations. That is, initially, mediation can be successful in ending dispute, however, very quickly, the effects drop substantially and the expected duration increases. After the dispute has then continued for some period, mediation begins to work toward shortening the dispute time again. 76 70 Sourdin, above n 18. 71 Ibid. 72 Ibid. 73 Ibid. 74 Ibid. 75 PM Regan and AC Stam, ‘In the Nick of Time: Conflict Management, Mediation Timing, and the Duration of Interstate Disputes’ (2000) 44(2) International Studies Quarterly 239, 253. 76 Ibid. 58 Source: P M Regan and A C Stam, ‘In the Nick of Time: Conflict Management, Mediation Timing, and the Duration of Interstate Disputes’ 44(2) International Studies Quarterly 239, 253. Despite the evidence which suggests that ADR generally can assist with decreasing the time it takes for a dispute to resolve (whether within the court and tribunal or outside of it), there are many elements which can obscure the findings in relation to timeliness and these primarily relate to the lack of system wide data. The lack of data also makes it difficult to examine whether obligations and requirements that have been placed on disputants to act in a ‘timely’, ‘efficient’, or ‘effective’ manner have been effective. In this context obligations also include requirements to act in particular ways if litigation is commenced. The obligations placed on various stakeholders through legislative reform, court-based initiatives and other reforms are often directed at fostering a culture that supports timely dispute resolution and finalisation 77 . Sometimes, obligations can be supported by cost sanctions – for instance, costs may be awarded against practitioners in respect of a failure to comply with obligations (see previous discussion). 78 The measures relating to the legal environments mentioned above have been referred to as a ‘cultural change’ exercise and in effect, this forms part of the framework necessary to change approaches to timeliness and civil justice. 79 The continuing lack of data issues make it difficult to 77 Sourdin, The Timeliness Project , above n 3. 78 See Civil Procedure Act 2005 (NSW). Under s 99, the court may take into account a legal practitioner’s failure to comply with requirements requiring the parties to assist the court to further the just, quick and cheap resolution of the real issues in the proceedings: Kendirjian v Ayoub [2008] NSWCA 194 (14 August 2008); Sourdin, The Timeliness Project, above n 3. 79 Sourdin, The Timeliness Project, above n 3. 59 determine how and whether these approaches have been effective and if not, what could be introduced to support cultures that foster timely approaches to dispute resolution. V: CONCLUSION AND FUTURE DIRECTIONS The nature of delay in the current justice environment is contingent on many aspects and mechanisms utilised by the modern justice system. These elements include information technology and electronic support, proactive intervention and management including case management systems as well as (ADR) for the resolution of civil, family and other disputes. The question of whether justice delayed is justice denied appears to depend on whether delay is inappropriate, out of proportion or avoidable. Proportionality and appropriateness of time taken to provide an outcome for disputants is said to form part of the definition of timeliness, as per the definition above. The discussion about delay and timeliness highlights some of the issues which are being and have been actively considered by stakeholders, commentators, courts and other justice actors. Many innovations have been directed at enhancing timeliness, where implemented with supporting mechanisms and sufficient resources, they appear to support a more efficient and proportionally timed justice experience for users. However, there are some challenges that must be surmounted in order to apply these systems (for example a lack of resources as well as the lack of consistent qualitative data about disputes), and in some cases there must be careful consideration as to the appropriateness of speedier process, versus other important interests (for example, public interest or other justice issues). First and foremost, better data collection and maintenance is required to provide the fundamental material for analysis as to what is avoidable and what is unavoidable delay. Only once this contextualisation is available, can innovations then be more logically applied and extended, to ensure that disputes can be resolved as quickly as possible, and with timelines that are appropriate, depending on the complexity and other characteristics of that dispute and the disputants. In addition, it will be important to ensure that there is an appropriate distinction between the concepts of time lapse and delay and that case management and other mechanisms are employed only in appropriate cases, where the delay is ‘avoidable’. Some commentators have suggested that the notions of ‘avoidable’ and ‘unavoidable’ are value laden concepts and must not be equated with what is warranted and what is unwarranted to ensure a meaningful and fair analysis of what is ‘avoidable’ or not 80 . Further, it is imperative that a balance is struck between timelines and quality of the justice experience and this can only be measured quantitatively, by engaging with, and hearing the voice of disputants and participants. Some commentators have suggested that in some instances, delay in some courts and tribunals might be inevitable, or at least are so at the moment due to a lack of court resources. As a result, other options for resolution, such as ADR may be increasingly recognised as a more efficient way to resolve many disputes. However clearly this is not a complete answer, a strong and timely 80 Arie Frieberg, comment made at Timeliness in the Justice System: Ideas and Innovations Forum, Monash University Law Chambers, 16-17 May 2014. 60 courts based system shapes the broader ADR sector and decision making across the community by shaping parameters and defining rights. Where judicial hearing and resolution of disputes takes place there needs to be recognition that this can be a time consuming and costly exercise. 81 In order to support public confidence in the justice system and the promise of timely justice, future directions must be ultimately geared toward the support required by justice agencies as well as the interests of disputants and participants in the justice system. 81 McClellan, above n 20. work_hkzvhkarkngebhfcb4w5suj7na ---- BOOK REVIEW 532 Notices of the AmericAN mAthemAticAl society Volume 67, Number 4 Emille Davie Lawrence is a term associate professor of mathematics and statistics at the University of San Francisco. Her email address is edlawrence@usfca.edu. Communicated by Notices Book Review Editor Stephan Ramon Garcia. For permission to reprint this article, please contact: reprint-permission @ams.org. DOI: https://dx.doi.org/10.1090/noti2062 a variety of courses with the essays and modules written by math faculty who have experience on the topic. I was happy to see that the authors took the time in the introduction to describe exactly what is meant by “teaching mathematics for social justice”: all mathematics instruction that aims to improve human well-being. Who could possibly deny the importance of improved human well-being!? This preemp- tively thwarts any social justice eye-rolling as well as sets the tone for the book. They also give the reader advice on how to use the text and extend an invitation to reach out to the contributing authors directly. The first essay is by Kira Hamman, and she is the only contributor who has both an essay and a module in the book. In “Mathematics in Service to Democracy” she out- lines how she had an aha moment after seeing people’s reaction to social disparities in New Orleans after Hurricane Katrina. She writes that she came to a personal realization that teaching mathematics must be about more than teaching students the chain rule, for example. We have a responsibility to help build an informed, civically engaged society. As a result, she developed courses on mathematics and democracy and quantitative information in the media. She spares all detail of the courses; rather, she stresses the importance of quantitative literacy in the K–16 system. Dave Kung makes a similar case for designing a math class to promote a mindful citizenry in “Math for Social Justice: A Last Math Class for Responsible Citizens.” He is guided by the question, “What mathematics do I want the person next to me in the voting booth to understand?” (motivated by an exchange in an Obama-McCain political debate). My favorite essay is from Victor Piercey. In “Quantitative Ethics,” Piercey describes his experiences in developing courses surrounding the moral and societal implications of how we use quantitative information. Piercey writes that in his course he challenges the students to place themselves into the decision-maker role instead of the consumer role by posing should questions: Should lenders reveal the implications of continually making only the minimum Mathematics for Social Justice: Resources for the College Classroom by Gizem Karaali and Lily S. Khadjavi I think we can all agree that we are currently living in a time of tectonic social and political shifts. Movements like #MeToo and Black Lives Matter have rightfully increased popular awareness of issues of inequity and marginal- ization. In the immortal words of Bob Dylan, “The times, they are a-changin’.” And for good reason. I’ve noticed some similar shifts in mathematics over the past few years. Not that connecting mathematics and social justice is a new concept, as this book attests by paying homage to Bob Moses’s Radical Equations: Math Literacy and Civil Rights in its first sentence. But one can also not deny the recent swell in scholarly activity surrounding the subject, which is why Mathematics for Social Justice: Resources for the College Classroom is such a timely and important tool. The cover of the book woos you, with its array of fists of different hues holding pencils in front of a backsplash of mathematical equations. The sheer brilliance of this image, which conjures resistance, unity, and mathematical rigor all at once, should not be lost on anyone. The contents of the book are divided into three parts: an introduction to the book by the authors, five essays that make the case for introducing topics of social justice into the math curricu- lum, and fourteen course modules that can be adopted into Mathematics for Social Justice Reviewed by Emille Davie Lawrence A M S/ M A A P re ss , 2 01 9 , S o ft co ve r, 2 7 7 p ag es . IS B N : 9 7 8 -1 -4 70 4 -4 9 2 6 -1 Book Review April 2020 Notices of the AmericAN mAthemAticAl society 533 You will find suggestions for homework assignments, worksheets, group projects, discussion topics, paper topics, final projects, and much more throughout. The book is also full of outside resources like readings, videos, websites, and such to make it easier to expand the modules in different or deeper directions. The utility of Mathematics for Social Justice: Resources for the College Classroom is undeniable. With this book, the editors and contributors have provided the mathematics community a toolkit for challenging students to use math- ematics to improve our world from many different angles. I would have liked to see a module focusing on overpolicing and criminal justice, since Khadjavi herself is versed in this topic, but perhaps that will come in the second volume that Karaali and Khadjavi are working on, Mathematics for Social Justice: Focusing on Quantitative Reasoning and Statistics. The current volume effectively makes the case that courses that include social justice themes should be a part of the curric- ulum in every math department in our country. I, for one, am personally energized and excited to implement these ideas at my institution. With this book as a guide, we can not only teach our students how to do math but also how to use math for the common good. Credits Author photo is courtesy of the author. payments on credit card debt? Should effective annual interest rates be required by law to be disclosed to consum- ers? Should environmental impacts to the community be considered when a company opens a store? How should the government intervene in Ponzi schemes? Students learn how questions like these are informed by data analysis and mathematical modeling. This ethical point of view feels to me like a fresh spin on things. Even the term quantitative ethics juxtaposes two ideas that I’d never before realized were compatible. Reading his essay gave me that “of course this works” feeling, like eating peanut butter and jelly for the first time. Of all the essays, Lisa Marano’s essay is the one I didn’t realize that I needed. She outlines in great detail how she has over the years dealt with student resistance to uncom- fortable topics. Since finding dy/dx is pretty noncontrover- sial, most math professors are unpracticed in dealing with issues in the classroom that stir up emotion. She gives class- room policies, assignment suggestions, and other general management strategies in preparation for “vocal, silent, and absent” resistance from students. Most effective is her use of real-life anecdotes to suggest how to guide students in heated discussions. One powerful example was how she dealt with some students’ personal trauma surrounding credit card debt. She explains that as the conversation began to unfold, she scrapped her planned discussion and yielded to the needs of the students. This is a reminder that since emotions can run high when digging in to social issues, being in the moment is key. Then come the modules. These are prepackaged and ready-to-go lesson plans that can be implemented in the classroom. I was really happy to see such a nice array of topics. There were definitely some usual suspects, such as modules on voting methods and electoral districting. How- ever, the majority of the topics feel cutting-edge and mod- ern, ranging from the graph theory of human trafficking to modeling the rise in acceptance of same-sex relationships. Although on different themes, every module has the same structure. Each starts with an abstract and is then divided into six sections: Mathematical Content, Context/Back- ground, Instructor Preparation, The Module, Additional Thoughts, and an Appendix. Having this uniformity is quite helpful to the reader who wants to compare one module to another. However, I would have also liked to see some note on the intended duration of each module right up front, perhaps in each abstract. Some modules seem more appropriate for just a handful of class meetings, while others could be implemented over the course of an entire academic term. Readers are left to figure this out for them- selves. The cherry-picking reader will be happy to know that in the postscript the modules are sorted by mathematical content, such as college algebra, quantitative reasoning, and introductory statistics, and then again by social justice themes, such as finance, environmental justice, and labor. The content of each module is pedagogically thorough. Emille Davie Lawrence work_hl5g73znanayxpgmid2nys7pm4 ---- jopp_205.qxd Responsibility and Global Labor Justice* Iris Marion Young Political Science, University of Chicago Socrates thought that, for the agent himself, doing wrong is more harmful than suffering wrong. Well, so long as it is merely a matter of ‘wrong’ done or suffered, thus a matter essentially existing in the perception of the parties, the proposition may stand. . . . But the objectified wrong creates a new, external causality, and we are inquiring about its moral harm to the suffering side. And we ask the question not, as Socrates did, for the single actions committed and suffered here and there, but for the constant effects on the victims of a system of justice. And there the main point is that, in a system of ruthless exploitation, those objective effects mean abject poverty with all the degradation, external and internal, which this entails. – Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility DO people in relatively free and affluent countries such as the United States,Canada or Germany have responsibilities to try to improve working conditions and wages of workers in far-off parts of the world who produce items those in the more affluent countries purchase? In recent years the “anti- sweatshop” movement has gained momentum with arguments that at least some agents in these relatively free and affluent countries do have such responsibilities. They have held rallies and press conferences, staged sit-ins and hunger strikes, all with the aim of convincing consumers, corporate executives, union members, municipal governments, students, and university administrators in the United States or Europe to acknowledge a responsibility with respect to the working conditions of distant workers in other countries, and to take actions to meet such responsibilities. Those to whom these appeals are made often find them absurd. We who go to work and school here in Chicago have no connection to workers in Bangkok or Manila or Tegucigalpa. However awful the conditions under which they work, we have not caused them, and we are not in control of the factors that would The Journal of Political Philosophy: Volume 12, Number 4, 2004, pp. 365–388 © Blackwell Publishing, 2004, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA. *Early versions of this essay were presented to the Central Division of the American Philosophical Association, the fellows’ seminar at the American Bar Foundation, the political theory workshop at Nuffield College, Oxford University, the political theory workshop at the London School of Economics, and the workshop of the University of Southern California Law School. I am grateful to the audiences who on those occasions asked hard questions. I am also grateful to the following individuals for their comments on earlier drafts: David Alexander, Jeremy Bendik-Keymer, Cecile Fabre, Robert Goodin, Jeffrey Isaac, Alison Jaggar, Melissa Lane, Liam Murphy, Thomas Pogge, Robert Pollin, Bill Scheuermann, Laurel Weldon, and anonymous reviewers for the Journal of Political Philosophy. Thanks to Matteo Colombi and Victor Muniz-Fraticelli for research assistance. remedy them. Thus it makes no sense to claim that we have moral responsibilities to try to change them. In this article I theorize a conception of responsibility that can make sense of the claims of the anti-sweatshop movement, or indeed, any claims of responsibility that members of a society might be said to have toward harms and injustices of distant strangers. Objectors to the anti-sweatshop movement are right to argue that these claims make little sense within a dominant conception of responsibility as liability. I propose and elaborate a different conception of responsibility, political responsibility, to correspond to these claims. I. CLAIMS OF RESPONSIBILITY FOR WORKING CONDITIONS Many of the goods sold by some of the most high-profile retailers in the United States, Canada, the United Kingdom, Japan and Germany are made in small factories far away in the Philippines, Sri Lanka, Guatemala, and other countries whose governments offer tax and other incentives to foreign investors. Others are manufactured in small production facilities in the United States employing immigrants. The American or Japanese brand name companies rarely operate the factories themselves, but rather place highly specified orders with other companies, who themselves often contract out the work to local entrepreneurs. Education and publicity about conditions under which much apparel sold in affluent countries is made in less developed countries has led to awareness that similar conditions in often illegally operating apparel manufacturing facilities exist in many cities closer to home—in Chicago, Los Angeles or New York, for example. The arguments I make here about responsibility apply to relations between strangers in the same country or city as much as transnationally. They are part of a connected global apparel industry system that produces both. In this paper I nevertheless concentrate the argument on transnational connection, because many people question that responsibility extends so far. It is not hyperbole to label these factories “sweatshops.” The vast majority of garment workers worldwide are women, often young women, who are readily accessible and relatively pliant from the employers’ point of view. Shifts are commonly at least ten hours, six days a week, and forced overtime is common. Factories usually have strict rules, which often include restrictions on talking and going to the bathroom, and supervisors are often abusive as a matter of policy. Working conditions are often dangerous, with poorly ventilated, overheated spaces and little protective equipment. Women workers often suffer sexual harassment or verbal abuse. Workers who protest their exploitation or attempt to organize unions are typically intimidated, beaten, or fired. Wages for these workers are often below the local legal minimum wage, and even when they are not, the wages fall below what the workers need for subsistence. Health benefits and pension plans are a fantastic dream, and there is no job security. Indeed, workers are often defined as temporary workers just so their employers can 366 IRIS MARION YOUNG legally escape the requirements of labor laws. According to a report from the International Labor Organization, dozens of millions of workers worldwide toil under such conditions.1 In the mid 1990s in the United States and Europe, activists began campaigns targeted at consumers of some of these products, to urge them to think about these far-away workers, not buy the products, and put pressure on the retailers that contracted their manufacture to change the working conditions. Leafleting and demonstrations at outlets of Gap, Disney, Nike and Victoria’s Secret caught the attention of some activists and consumers, and eventually succeeded in moving corporate leaders to take some actions in response, although some have described these as cosmetic. Initially, however, the global companies’ response was to deny responsibility for the workers, saying that they did not themselves operate the factories in which the goods were produced. In the meantime, students at colleges and universities raised questions about the conditions under which the garments worn by their sports teams and sold in their bookstores are made. They called upon their university administrations to terminate contracts with sportswear companies that refused to take responsibility for such conditions. The height of the student anti-sweatshop movement came during the 1999–2000 academic year, when student groups on hundreds of campuses held rallies and campus education events, occupied administration buildings and staged hunger strikes. Most of the student groups were demanding that their universities join the Workers’ Rights Coalition, a student-initiated independent organization to monitor working conditions in apparel factories overseas, and to put pressure on manufacturers to change poor conditions. Many students and college administrators responded to these demands with incredulity.2 It is not the business of universities and their students to get involved in labor regulation, especially of conditions so remote. We are not the cause of the injustice the workers suffer, and we do not control those who are. The owners and managers of the factories clearly have a primary responsibility for the treatment workers receive, the hours they are required to work, their wages and benefits, and the safety of the work environment. They make specific cost minimization decisions that result in sweatshop conditions, they make the rules that prohibit bathroom breaks or days off, they lock the doors and verbally abuse the workers, they or those they hire threaten and beat workers who try to organize unions. If there are any agents to blame for the plight of these workers, surely the owners and managers must be first in line. Inasmuch as its primary recommendation for action to improve the workers’ RESPONSIBILITY & GLOBAL LABOR JUSTICE 367 1For an account of working conditions, see Ellen Israel Rosen, Making Sweatshops: The Globalization of the U.S. Apparel Industry (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2002), ch. 2; Edna Bonacich and Richard P. Appelbaum, Behind the Label: Inequality in the Los Angeles Apparel Industry (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2002), esp. ch. 6; Naomi Klein, No Logo (New York: Picador, 1999), esp. ch. 9. 2Lisa Fetherstone, Students Against Sweatshops (London: Verso, 2000). situation is that universities and corporations should monitor factory conditions and pressure the owners and managers to change their policies, the anti- sweatshop movement recognizes that those agents have a direct responsibility. Such a rejection of movement claims of the responsibility of university administrators and consumers assumes a liability model of responsibility. On the liability model, it is indeed implausible to hold these remote agents responsible for the workers’ situation. The anti-sweatshop movement must implicitly be relying on another conception of responsibility. My project here is to construct a conception of responsibility that corresponds to their intuitions, which I call political responsibility. My argument is not that the concept of political responsibility should replace that of a fault or liability model, but should supplement that model in analyses of responsibility in relation to structural processes. The most common model of assigning responsibility derives from legal reasoning to find guilt or fault for a harm. Under the fault model, one assigns responsibility to particular agents whose actions can be shown as causally connected to the circumstances for which responsibility is sought. This agent can be a collective entity, such as a corporation, but when it is that entity can be treated as a single agent for the purposes of assigning responsibility.3 The actions found causally connected to the circumstances are shown to be voluntary. If a candidate for responsibility can successfully show that their causal relation to the circumstances was not voluntary, that they were coerced or otherwise did not evince free choice, then their responsibility is usually mitigated if not dissolved. When these conditions do exist, however, it is appropriate to blame the agents for the harmful circumstances. A concept of strict liability departs from a fault or blame model in that it holds a person liable for an action that caused a harm even if they did not intend the outcome, or holds a person or institution liable for a harm caused by someone under their command.4 I include both fault liability and strict liability in the liability model of responsibility, because they share other features that I will use to distinguish this model from the model of political responsibility. The liability model is primarily backward- looking in its purpose; it reviews the history of events in order to assign responsibility, often for the sake of exacting punishment or compensation. Assigning responsibility to some agents, on this model, finally, usually also has the function of absolving other agents who might have been candidates for fault. To find this person or group of persons guilty of a crime usually implies that others who were accused are not guilty. 368 IRIS MARION YOUNG 3See Peter French, Collective and Corporate Responsibility (New York: Columbia University Press, 1984). 4On concepts of fault and liability see, for example, Joel Feinberg, “Collective responsibility,” Doing and Deserving: Essays in the Theory of Responsibility (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1970), pp. 222–51; Tony Honoré, “Responsibility and luck: the moral basis of strict liability,” Responsibility and Fault (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), pp. 14–40. Because their decisions and actions are the immediate and repeated cause of factory conditions, the owners and managers of these factories are certainly the prime candidate for blame if these conditions violate minimal standards of decency and human rights. Local firms that directly buy from these enterprises, who presumably are the most likely to know about such violations, probably should also be held responsible. When confronted with accusations that they wrongly exploit and oppress their workers, however, some of these agents are likely to try to mitigate their responsibility by appeal to factors outside their control. They may claim that they have little choice about the wages they pay, and cannot afford to give workers time off or invest in better ventilation and equipment. They operate in a highly competitive environment, they say, where other operators constantly try to undercut them. They can stay in business only by selling goods at or below the prices of worldwide competitors, and they can do that only by keeping labor and other production costs to a minimum. Apparel dealers who sell to American wholesalers are looking for the best deal, and they will take their business elsewhere if these employers raise their prices. Surely it cannot be better for the workers that they have no job at all, these employers are likely to claim.5 Such an appeal to mitigating circumstances can only go so far, of course. No employer can legitimately excuse making people work sixteen-hour days, refusing them bathroom breaks, or beating them, as necessary for keeping the costs of production competitive. Nevertheless, there is a good measure of truth to the claim that these employers themselves operate under considerable constraints. Many of these factories do operate on the edge of solvency, in a highly competitive environment. Under such circumstances of anarchistic competition, labor rights advocates might turn to the states in whose jurisdictions the factories operate. A typical justification for state-enforced labor standards appeals to the need to maintain a level playing field among competitors. If there is a human rights floor below which wages and working conditions should not be allowed to fall, the state is the proper agent to guarantee such a floor through regulation. In this way those employers who wish to be decent to workers need not fear being undersold by more unscrupulous employers. Certainly the states in which sweatshops operate must be blamed for allowing them to exist. Many of these state agencies are inept and corrupt, and often enough some of their officials directly profit from the system that exploits their poor compatriots. As the movement uncovers sweatshops in the United States and other states with supposedly high labor standards and good enforcement processes, it should certainly blame these agencies for not doing their jobs. Some states not unreasonably say, however, that they themselves are under severe constraints that prevent them from improving working conditions. Many RESPONSIBILITY & GLOBAL LABOR JUSTICE 369 5See Rosen, Making Sweatshops, ch. 11 and Bonacich and Appelbaum, Behind the Label, chs 2 and 5 for an account of constraints on actors in the system. governments of less developed countries have indirectly encouraged these very practices by constituting special export processing zones whose factories are exempt from taxation and regulation that apply to other enterprises in the country. We desperately need investment and jobs, they say. To get them we are forced to compete with other poor states to promote a “favorable” investment climate, which includes low taxes and minimal regulation. To avoid or pay down balance of trade deficits they need companies that produce for export. They have never had a strong enough public sector properly to monitor and enforce compliance with their regulations, and it is difficult to create one with their low tax base. Their bureaucrats and inspectors are overworked and underpaid themselves, and thus easily succumb to bribe offers. Pressures for reduced public spending by international financial institutions such as the International Monetary Fund have further weakened public sector capacity. Owners, managers and local states are the agents that should be held liable for superexploitative and oppressive working conditions in which many items consumed by people in North America and Europe are produced. When these agents claim that they operate under constraints beyond their control that give them few options to operate factories differently, however, there is some basis for their excuses. They point to structural economic and political processes involving actors and institutions both inside and outside the countries that host the factories, whose processes and effects both enable and provide incentives for some actions at the same time as they block or constrain alternatives. The factories where the workers labor operate within a dense system of investment, production, credit, exchange and profit which connect direct producers to far away consumers, and link local brokers and middlemen to multinational corporate marketing plans. Activists in the anti-sweatshop movement claim that we relatively affluent people in the global North share responsibility for the fate of the faraway workers because these structural processes connect us to them. What does such connection mean and why does it bring responsibilities? What is the nature of these responsibilities? In the next section I will build on analyses some moral theorists of international justice have offered of transnational connection that bring with them moral responsibilities. Then I will explain how these are political responsibilities, as distinct from liabilities, and explain differences in these two concepts of responsibility. In the final section I will explain how the model of political responsibility might be applied to reasoning about how particular agents should respond to structural injustices. II. INTERNATIONAL JUSTICE Activists’ claims that university administrators, corporate executives, students and consumers in Europe and North America have responsibilities toward workers in faraway lands excite controversy partly because they presuppose a strong notion of moral responsibility between agents in different nations 370 IRIS MARION YOUNG and political communities. Many people reject the idea of such transnational responsibilities, believing that the requirement to rectify injustice toward others extends only to those who live within the same political jurisdiction and/or share a sense of common national membership. Are there grounds for the assumption that some obligations of justice extend globally and that therefore better-off people in some parts of the world have responsibilities toward globally worse- off people wherever they are? I will build on arguments of Onora O’Neill and Thomas Pogge that there are.6 Onora O’Neill argues that the scope of an agent’s moral obligation extends to all those whom the agent assumes in conducting his or her activity. Each of us acts according to interests and goals we set within the frame of specific institutions and practices, within which we know others act. Our actions are partly based on the actions of others, insofar as we depend on them to carry out certain tasks, and/or insofar as our general knowledge of what other people are doing enable us to formulate expectations and predictions about events and institutional outcomes that affect us or condition our actions. In today’s world of globalized markets, interdependent states, rapid and dense communication, the scope of the actors we implicitly assume in many of our actions is often global. The social relations that connect us to others are not restricted to nation–state borders. Our actions are conditioned by and contribute to institutions that affect distant others, and their actions contribute to the operation of institutions that affect us. Because our actions assume these others as a condition for our own actions, O’Neill argues, we have made practical moral commitments to them by virtue of our actions. While it is not possible to trace how each person’s actions produce specific effects on others, because there are too many mediating actions and events, we have obligations to those who condition and enable our own actions, as they do on us. There is an asymmetry in these obligations, however, O’Neill argues, insofar as some people are rendered more vulnerable to coercion, domination or deprivation by the institutional relations. While everyone in the system of structural and institutional relations stands in circumstances of justice that give them obligations with respect to all the others, those institutionally and materially situated to be able to do more to affect the conditions of vulnerability have greater obligations.7 Important for O’Neill’s analysis and the use I want to make of it, these presuppositions of activity need not be present to an agent’s consciousness in order to hold as assumptions. These relationships are objective. Although most of us are often unaware of or indifferent to the situation of those whose activities RESPONSIBILITY & GLOBAL LABOR JUSTICE 371 6I have discussed the same authors’ arguments at some more length and in a wider context of global justice in Inclusion and Democracy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), ch. 7. 7Onora O’Neill, Faces of Hunger (London: Allen and Unwin, 1985); Towards Justice and Virtue (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), p. 99; compare Robert Goodin, Protecting the Vulnerable (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1985). condition our own options for action, this does not erase the potential obligations we have toward these others. It is not uncommon for agents to deny the connection to others their actions assume, but such efforts at bad faith are pragmatically inconsistent. If I implicitly depend on anonymous others to fulfill their roles or occupy their statuses as I conduct my business, I cannot deny this connection if they should make claims upon me to redress injustices they claim to suffer in the institutions we inhabit together. Moral critique of both individuals and institutions consists to a significant extent in bringing to consciousness the assumptions about others that agents make in their activities, and exposing the inconsistency between these assumptions and the denials of connection.8 This method of discovering responsibility to others applies easily to the context of apparel purchase. When I buy a sweatshirt or a pair of shoes, my action presupposes the actions of all the persons connected with the process that transforms raw materials into clothes and brings them to my local store. When I look for low-priced clothes, I presuppose the actions of those who make decisions to minimize costs of production, decisions like failing to equip garment factories with smoke detectors and sprinklers. On O’Neill’s account, because I am connected to all these people through my consumer actions, I have obligations of justice toward them. I cannot escape these obligations by claiming that I have not participated in design of the relations of production and distribution, nor by saying that I do not know where or who all these people are. I know that they are others elsewhere, that I am connected with them in these institutions and processes, and that especially workers in these processes are vulnerable to harm from employers and others. My first responsibility may be to acquire more specific knowledge. As I will discuss shortly, I share responsibility with the many others who also contribute by their actions to the processes that connect us. Just because I cannot disentangle my particular actions from the complex process in which some people are made particularly vulnerable to deprivation or domination, to identify which specific actions of mine affect which specific individuals in particular ways, I have a relation of responsibility to the process itself. Charles Beitz and Thomas Pogge also offer accounts of the bases of a claim that people within one nation–state have responsibilities of justice toward many people in other nation–states. People in relatively affluent countries act within a transnational system of interdependence and dense economic interaction, which has systemic consequences for the relative privilege and disadvantage that people experience in different parts of the world or within particular locales. The grounds of moral responsibility lie neither in political structures of the nation–state nor in people’s awareness and affirmation of a connection to others, but in the objective systemic institutional relations in which they dwell together 372 IRIS MARION YOUNG 8Towards Justice and Virtue, ch. 4. with distance to others. Pogge in particular argues that persons who live in more affluent industrial parts of the world act within a common institutional scheme with persons who live in less industrialized parts of the world. The global poor live within a world wide states system based on internationally recognized territorial domains, interconnected through a global network of market trade and diplomacy. The presence and relevance of shared institutions is shown by how dramatically we affect the circumstances of the global poor through investments, loans, trade, brides, military aid, sex tourism, culture exports and much else. Their very survival often crucially depends on our consumption choices, which may determine the price of their foodstuffs and their opportunity to find work. . . . This does not mean that we should hold ourselves responsible for the remoter effects of our economic decisions. . . . But we must be concerned with how the rules structuring international interactions foreseeable affect the incidence of extreme poverty.9 Later I will argue that some of Pogge’s formulations of the moral relationships between such agents in the global North and some of the world’s poor and working people are somewhat misleading. To summarize so far, these philosophers theorize a complex set of structural relations across the globe which condition the material circumstances and possibilities for action of most of the world’s people. Reciprocal obligations of justice obtain between most if not all of these people not simply because they are human nor because they live under the same political constitution, but because they all depend to some degree on schemes of social cooperation which they presuppose in making their own plans or to which they contribute by their actions. Within this global “basic structure,” however, some people have significantly more power than others, not only over the conditions of their own lives, but also over decisions and processes that affect others. Within the structures, furthermore, some people occupy positions of privilege while others are relatively or absolutely deprived. Samuel Scheffler suggests that facts of global interdependence like these make fundamental features of the common sense conception of responsibility problematic. That common sense conception of responsibility is restrictive; it aims to delimit a relatively circumscribed sphere of circumstances and persons toward which agents have responsibility. This conception tends to restrict responsibility to what individuals themselves do, as opposed to what they fail to prevent. It also tends to restrict responsibility to those persons with whom an agent has special or relatively immediate connection—members of one’s family, one’s coworkers, one’s neighbors, and others with whom one has ongoing interaction.10 A particular phenomenology of agency underlies this conception RESPONSIBILITY & GLOBAL LABOR JUSTICE 373 9Thomas Pogge, “A universalistic approach to international justice,” Internationale Gerechtigkeit und Interpretation, ed. Giuseppe Zaccaria (Munchen: WT Verlag, 2002), Section 2.1; ed. Charles Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979). 10Scheffler includes members of the same nation–state in the category of these special relationships, but I think this is a mistake. of responsibility, according to Scheffler, which gives experiential primacy to near effects rather than remote effects of action. When “an outcome is the joint result of the actions of a number of people, including ourselves, we tend to see our own agency as implicated to a much lesser extent than we do when we take an effect to have resulted solely from our own actions.”11 This phenomenology of agency and the conception of responsibility it supports, Scheffler argues, does not correspond well to the issues that face moral agents because of the density of communication, economic exchange, technological effects, migration, and political interaction among the world’s people. Because the common sense conception of responsibility, which corresponds in significant ways to what I call the liability model, has little to say in relation to such massive global issues, Scheffler suggests, we are in danger of losing a sense of individuals as bearers of responsibility altogether. What we appear to lack, in other words, is a set of clear, action-guiding and psychologically feasible principles which would enable individuals to orient themselves in relation to larger processes, and general conformity to which would serve to regulate those processes and their effects in a morally satisfactory way.12 I am not convinced that what we need to respond to this predicament is a set of principles to which individuals might look for guidance about what to do in relation to global social processes. Scheffler has nevertheless identified a key problem in contemporary moral theory and practice. People have difficulty reasoning about individual responsibility with relation to outcomes produced by large-scale social structures in which millions participate, but of which none are the sole or primary cause. When these structures are transnational, as many of them are, the difficulty is compounded by a relative lack of regulatory institutions through which these millions might engage in collective action. It is this difficulty that accounts for our continuing to rely solely on a liability model of responsibility for harms, I suggest, as in debates about transnational labor conditions. In the following section I begin to articulate a model of political responsibility which goes some distance toward ways that individuals can think about their responsibilities in relation to global social structures. III. POLITICAL RESPONSIBILITY I have argued that local owners and managers of factories with superexploitative working conditions should be held responsible for those conditions. Their actions causally contribute most directly to the workers’ situation, and they should be blamed for it. I have also argued, however, that workers, owners 374 IRIS MARION YOUNG 11Scheffler, “Individual responsibility in a global age,” Boundaries and Allegiances: Problems of Responsibility and Justice in Liberal Thought (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001) p. 39. 12Ibid. and even the nation–states that have jurisdiction over them are embedded in transnational economic structures which connect individuals and institutions in faraway corporate boardrooms and retail outlets to them. These structural conditions provide incentives for setting up and buying from manufacturing operations that violate worker rights. Blaming and punishing a few factory owners, while often appropriate, does not remedy the general problem so long as that incentive structure is in place and sanction is not routine. These economic structures constrain the options of owners and managers in the less developed countries, and implicate many others in the world in the processes that produce those constraints. Because of these connections, activists claim that consumers, corporate executives, university administrators and others in Europe, North America, Japan, and other relatively well-off places have responsibilities toward the working conditions of apparel factories in South Asia, Latin America and elsewhere. This claim only makes sense, I suggested earlier, if the faraway consumers, executives, and administrations bear responsibility in a different sense from the owners and managers of the factories. Earlier I said that the owners and managers are responsible for the working conditions in the sense of liability. The liability model of responsibility causally connects the circumstances for which responsibility is sought with specific actions of particular agents. In this sense the liability model individualizes even when the agent it identifies is a corporate entity. The liability model is backward-looking; it seeks to lay blame for harms that have occurred, often for the sake of exacting punishment or compensation. The many agents whom O’Neill or Pogge would identify as connected with the transnational institutions and structures that help bring sweatshop conditions about have responsibilities for harmful or unjust conditions in a different sense, which I will call political responsibility. Hannah Arendt distinguishes between moral and legal responsibility, on the one hand, which embody what I have called the liability model, and what she calls political responsibility, on the other. On her account, political responsibility is a kind of collective responsibility, and one where the responsibility borne collectively is not dissolvable to the self-conscious collaborative acts of individuals. Whereas responsibility as liability assigns responsibility according to what particular agents have done, on the model of political responsibility individuals are responsible precisely for things they themselves have not done. The reason to assume political responsibility involves not individual fault, but derives from “my membership in a group (a collective) which no voluntary act of mine can dissolve, that is, a membership which is utterly unlike a business partnership which I can dissolve at will.”13 Arendt clearly takes the political community of a nation–state as her paradigm of such a collective. RESPONSIBILITY & GLOBAL LABOR JUSTICE 375 13Hannah Arendt, “Collective responsibility,” Amor Mundi: Explorations in the Faith and Thought of Hannah Arendt, ed. James W. Bernauer (Boston: Martinus Nijoff, 1987), p. 45. We can escape this political and strictly collective responsibility only by leaving the community, and since no man can live without belonging to some community, this would simply mean to exchange some community for another and hence one kind of responsibility for another.14 As a member of such a political community we are bound to acknowledge that we bear responsibility for things our government does in our name or supposedly on our behalf, even though we ourselves have not done those things, and even though the actions may not be connected to any process of authorization that even indirectly links them to us. Arendt seems to think that being members of a national or political community just in itself is the ground of this responsibility. Along similar lines, some political philosophers as well as many political actors distinguish the kind and level of responsibilities people have in relation to one another precisely on grounds of being members of the same nation–state or not. Whereas people owe only the thinnest form of respect and decency to one another across borders, the fact of shared national membership puts special responsibilities on persons to be concerned for the welfare of their fellow countrymen, and that they live together on terms of justice. This manner of viewing responsibilities for promoting justice and the wellbeing of others reasons backwards. If there are denser and more demanding responsibilities between members of the same nation–state than between members of faraway societies, this is because the processes and structures in which they are embedded more tightly connect them, and the consequences of their actions affect the more local others than those far away. Common polities form or ought to form in these situations of dense structures in order that people may collectively regulate those interactions in ways they judge most just. The political responsibilities derive, that is, not from the contingent fact of membership in common political institutions. Instead, the political responsibilities derive from the social and economic structures in which they act and mutually affect one another, and political institutions are an important means of their discharging those responsibilities. Much of the sociological and moral theoretical literature on processes of globalization aims to show that the structural connections among persons in the world have both widened their scope beyond nation–state boundaries and become more dense across these boundaries. To the extent that people here participate in the production and reproduction of structural processes that condition the lives of people far away, however, the sort of political responsibilities that Arendt invokes exist for them in relation to those distant others. While they probably have not intended that the social processes in which they participate and from which they benefit have harmful consequences to 376 IRIS MARION YOUNG 14Ibid, p. 47. others, and they should not be blamed or found guilty for these consequences, they are responsible under a different conception. Despite my disagreement with Arendt on the question of whether the ground of this form of responsibility lies in being members of the same nation–state, I continue to follow her in labeling this political responsibility for the following reasons. As does Arendt in many contexts, I mean by “political” something broader than government. In addition, by politics or the political I am referring to the activity in which people organize collectively to regulate or transform some aspect of their shared social conditions, along with the communicative activities in which they try to persuade one another to join such collective action or decide what direction they wish to take it. The sort of responsibility that anti-sweatshop activists claim that they, their fellow consumers, and specific institutions of manufacture or distribution of goods have is political responsibility in this sense. Now I will detail the features of this conception of responsibility, especially as distinct from the fault or liability model of responsibility. (1) Unlike a blame model of responsibility, political responsibility does not seek to mark out and isolate those to be held responsible, thereby distinguishing them from others, who by implication then are not responsible. Such isolation of the one liable from the others who are not is an important aspect of legal responsibility, both in criminal and in tort law. Because they argue that organizations or collectives of persons can be blamed for harms, as well as individual persons, most accounts of collective responsibility aim to distinguish those who have done the harm from those who have not. In the discussion cited above, Arendt says that political responsibility, on the other hand, is a responsibility for what we have not done. This may be a mystifying and even misleading way of putting the point, which I take to be the following. Many cases of harms, wrongs or injustice have no isolatable perpetrator, but rather result from the participation of millions of people in institutions and practices that result in harms. Endemic large-scale homelessness in an otherwise affluent society might be an example of such an injustice without an identifiable perpetrator. In many cases where perpetrators of specific crimes can and should be identified, moreover, as in the Nazi Holocaust Arendt has in mind, the makers of genocidal policies and those that directly implement them are enabled and supported by wider social structures in which many participate. I have suggested already that the injustices of inhumane labor conditions should be analyzed on these two levels. In the conception of political responsibility, then, finding that some people bear responsibility for injustice does not necessarily absolve others. (2) In a liability conception of responsibility, what counts as a wrong for which a perpetrator is sought and for which he or she might be required to compensate, is generally conceived as a deviation from a baseline. Implicitly we assume a normal background situation that is morally acceptable, if not ideal. A crime or RESPONSIBILITY & GLOBAL LABOR JUSTICE 377 an actionable harm consists in a morally and often legally unacceptable deviation from this background structure.15 The process that brought about the harm is conceived as a discrete, bounded event that breaks away from the ongoing normal flow. Punishment, redress, or compensation aims to restore normality or to “make whole” in relation to the baseline circumstance. A concept of political responsibility in relation to structural injustices, on the other hand, evaluates not a harm that deviates from the normal and acceptable, but rather often brings into question precisely the background conditions that ascriptions of blame or fault assume as normal. When we judge that structural injustice exists, we are saying precisely that at least some of the normal and accepted background conditions of action are not morally acceptable. Most of us contribute to a greater or lesser degree to the production and reproduction of structural injustice precisely because we follow the accepted and expected rules and conventions of the communities and institutions in which we act. Usually we enact these conventions and practices in a habitual way, without explicit reflection and deliberation on what we are doing, having in the foreground of our consciousness and intention immediate goals we want to achieve and the particular people we need to interact with to achieve them. The anti-sweatshop movement well illustrates this challenge to normal structural background conditions. It asks consumers, universities and other institutions that contract with retailers, brand name apparel companies, and many other agents, to reflect morally on the normal and hitherto acceptable market relationships in which they act. It challenges all the agents that are part of the economic chain between the workers who make garments and the people who buy and wear them to bring into question whether “business as usual”, which hitherto has been understood as within the bounds of moral acceptability, should in fact be thought acceptable. (3) Political responsibility, furthermore, differs from a liability model of responsibility in being more forward-looking than backward-looking. Blame and praise are primarily backward-looking judgments. They refer back to an action or event assumed to have reached its terminus. More often the purpose of assigning responsibility as fault or liability is to sanction, punish or exact compensation from them. To be sure, such backward-looking condemnation and sanction may have a forward-looking purpose; we may wish to deter others from similar action in the future, or we may wish to identify weak points in an institutional system that allows or encourages such blameworthy actions, in order to reform the institutions. Once we take this latter step, however, we have left a liability model and are moving toward a conception of political responsibility. The reform project likely involves responsibilities of many people 378 IRIS MARION YOUNG 15See George Fletcher’s discussion of the way that the assignment of criminal liability must distinguish between foregrounded deviations from background conditions assumed as normal. Fletcher, Basic Concepts of Criminal Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998), chs 3 and 4. to take actions directed at those reforms, even though they are not to blame for past problems. Political responsibility seeks not to reckon debts, but aims rather to bring about results, and thus depends on the actions of everyone who is in a position to contribute to the results.16 Taking political responsibility in respect to social structures emphasizes the future more than the past. Because the particular causal relationship of the actions of particular individuals or even organizations to the structural outcomes is often not possible to trace, there may be little point in trying to blame and exact compensation or redress only from a few who have caused the outcome. The point is not to blame people participating in the institutions and structures and produce injustice, because in many cases avoiding such participation is difficult or impossible. Having understood that structural processes cause some injustices, those participating in the production and reproduction of the structures should recognize that their actions contribute along with those of others to this injustice, and take responsibility for altering the processes to avoid or reduce injustice. Such a project cannot be undertaken, of course, without reflection on the past in a different way. In order to take forward-looking action aimed at changing the way that people’s actions in the context of accepted institutional practices contribute to harmful outcomes, we must understand more about how the structural processes work. This usually requires understanding the history of social processes and practices as they have emerged, changed, influenced one another, and often produced unintended outcomes. The primary purpose of such backward-looking analysis in the context of political responsibility, however, is not to debate fault, which can divert those who share political responsibility from the forward-looking tasks of trying to alter the processes. (4) Political responsibility is relatively open with regard to the actions that count as taking up the responsibility. In this respect, as Joel Feinberg discusses, responsibility is distinct from duty. Like duties, responsibilities carry a burden and an obligation; carrying out responsibilities is not a matter of mere beneficence. Unlike duties, however, responsibilities carry considerable discretion; one must carry out one’s responsibilities, but how one does so is a matter for judgment according to what the responsibilities are for, the capabilities of agents, and the content of action.17 Similarly, Robert Goodin argues that responsibility differs from duty in being more outcome oriented. A duty specifies a rule that an agent should follow. One has fulfilled the duty if one has performed the required actions. Carrying out a responsibility, on the other hand, consists in seeking to bring about a specified outcome. It is very possible to act in accord RESPONSIBILITY & GLOBAL LABOR JUSTICE 379 16See Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), pp. 90–120. 17Joel Feinberg, “Duties, rights and claims,” Rights, Justice and the Bounds of Liberty (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1980), p. 137; cited in Larry May, The Socially Responsible Self: Social Theory and Professional Ethics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1996), p. 90. with rules of morality and yet not have discharged one’s responsibilities, because one has not achieved the required outcomes even though it is feasible to do so.18 (5) Political responsibility, then, is a shared responsibility in specific ways. As Larry May theorizes, the concept of shared responsibility is distinct from the concept of collective responsibility in that the former is a distributed responsibility whereas the latter is not. A collective of persons, such as a corporation, might be said to be responsible for a state of affairs without any of its constituent individuals being responsible as such. Shared responsibility, on the other hand, is a personal responsibility for outcomes or the risks of harmful outcomes, produced by a group of persons. Each is personally responsible for the outcome in a partial way, since he or she alone does not produce the outcomes; the specific part that each plays in producing the outcome cannot be isolated and identified, however, and thus the responsibility is essentially shared.19 May’s treatment of shared responsibility is largely backward-looking. He reflects on how persons who have not themselves been directly guilty of a harm such as a hate crime may nevertheless contribute by their attitudes and actions to fostering a social environment in which such harms appear more acceptable than they might otherwise. If we follow my claim that political responsibility is more forward-looking than backward-looking, then the shared nature of political responsibility refers primarily to the relationships with others that the responsibility involves. Taking political responsibility means acknowledging that one participates in social processes that have some unjust outcomes, and one participates with many others. Discharging the responsibility entails enjoining collective action with at least some of these others. My responsibility becomes to enjoin others to reflect on and acknowledge their participation in the structural processes, and to listen to their account of how they work and our role in them. We share responsibility to fashion organized means of changing how the processes work so they will issue in less injustice. Our working through state institutions is often an effective means of such collective action to change structural processes, but states are not the only tools of effective collective action.20 The form of responsibility, then, is political in these senses that acting on my responsibilities involves joining with others in a public discourse where we try to persuade one another about courses of collective action that will contribute to ameliorating the problem. 380 IRIS MARION YOUNG 18Robert Goodin, “Responsibilities,” Utilitarianism as a Public Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995), pp. 81–7. 19May, Sharing Responsibility (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993), ch. 2. 20Melanie Beth Oliviero and Adele Simmons recommend uses of civil society organizations for addressing issues of labor standards; see “Who’s minding the store? Global civil society and corporate responsibility,” Global Civil Society 2002, ed. Marlies Glasius, Mary Kaldo and Helmut Anheier (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002), pp. 77–107. Archon Fung develops a model for a process of improving labor conditions that combines state institutions and decentralized deliberative civic organizations, including those involving affected workers; Fung, “Deliberative democracy and international labor standards,” Governance, 16 (2003), 51–71. An important corollary of this feature of political responsibility is that many of those properly thought to be victims of harm or injustice may nevertheless have political responsibility in relation to it. In a fault model of responsibility, blaming those who claim to be victims of injustice functions to absolve others of responsibility for their plight. In a conception of political responsibility, however, those who can properly be argued as victims of structural injustice can be called to a responsibility they share with others in the structures to engage in actions directed at transforming the structures. In the case of labor exploitation, the workers themselves ought to resist if they can by means of their own collective organization. Without the support of others taking responsibility for working conditions in ways that support them, however, they are less likely to succeed. Conceptualizing political responsibility as distinct from blame is important not only philosophically, but also for the sake of motivating political action. Frequently the reaction of people being blamed for a wrong is defensive—to look for other agents who should be blamed instead of them, or to find excuses that mitigate their liability in those cases where they must agree that their actions do causally contribute to the harm. Such practices of accusation and defense have an important place in morality and law. In many contexts where the issue is how to mobilize collective action for the sake of social change and greater justice, however, such rhetorics of blame and finger-pointing displacement lead more to resentment and refusal to take responsibility than to useful basis of action. If corporate executives or shoe buyers hear the claims of anti-sweatshop activists as laying blame on them personally for the conditions under which the shoes are produced, they rightly become indignant, or scoff at the absurd extremism of the movement. A concept of political responsibility separate from and additional to responsibility as liability allows us to call on one another to take responsibility together for the fact that our actions collectively assume and contribute to the complex structural processes that enable the working conditions we deplore and make them difficult for any single agent to change.21 As I discuss in the next section, this does not necessarily imply that all who share responsibility have an equal responsibility. The power to influence the processes that produce unjust outcomes is an important factor distinguishing degrees of responsibility. Earlier I suggested that some of Thomas Pogge’s formulation of the responsibilities of global justice wrongly slip into a blame-oriented language. RESPONSIBILITY & GLOBAL LABOR JUSTICE 381 21William Connolly makes a distinction similar to Arendt’s between responsibility as blame and political responsibility. For him the resentment and count-accusation dialectic that accompanies blame in a discourse of public affairs makes political identity overly rigid and paralyzes action. Thus he recommends a notion of political responsibility without blame and with a more fluid and ambiguous understanding of the sources of wrong than the implicitly Christian identification of the sinner. See Connolly, Identity/Difference (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1993), esp. ch. 4. Melissa Orlie also distinguishes between a sentiment of resentment exhibited in blaming and holding oneself and others politically responsible. See Orlie, Living Ethically, Acting Politically (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1997), pp. 169–73. Briefly examining how can help clarify why the distinction is important. In some of his discussions Pogge conceives the institutions and social processes in which most of the world’s people are embedded as a system that is imposed by some on others. He finds a small global elite—affluent citizens and holders of political and economic power in resource-rich developed countries—who “enforce a global poverty regime under which we may claim the world’s natural resources for ourselves and can distribute these among ourselves on mutually agreeable terms.”22 He refers to “the design of a global economic order” which is determined by a tiny minority of participants, and finds that a global economic order is being imposed on people in developing countries by Western governments acting in the name of their citizens, which presses many people into grinding poverty and exposes them to domination.23 The language of design, enforcement and imposition in these formulations encourages a reversion to a liability model of responsibility for global economic relations. If “we” impose an unjust order on “them,” then we should be blamed for this wrong. Certainly some particular agents can and should be blamed for specific decisions they make and actions they take whose consequences in worsening the lives of poor people can be traced. Perhaps we should blame decision-makers at the International Monetary Fund, for example, for the consequences on poor people of the harsh conditions they impose on states in the service of structural adjustment. It is not helpful, however, to construct the entire network of economic interdependence that links North American consumers to East Asian workers as a design wrongly imposed on others for which some people can be blamed. Implicitly such a formulation absolves too many ordinary people, in the South as well as the North, of responsibilities they should take up, if only responsibilities to organize pressure on powerful global actors. So how does the model of political responsibility apply to the claims of the anti-sweatshop movement? I said earlier that local owners and managers, and to some extent the local state, should be held responsible in the sense of liable for the miserable pay and working conditions of factories where many consumer goods exported to the United States and Europe are produced. Political responsibility adds to rather than replaces this first layer of responsibility. Because corporate executives, university administrations, retailers, and consumers act within a set of structures that materially connect them to one another and to factory workers, they have responsibilities to concern themselves with the wellbeing of those workers. Acknowledging such political responsibility does not imply accepting blame for being a direct cause of the poor conditions. It does mean acknowledging that they contribute by their actions to perpetuating the structural conditions, incentives and constraints that condition the actions 382 IRIS MARION YOUNG 22Thomas Pagge, World Poverty and Human Rights (Cambridge Polity Press, 2002), p. 142. 23“Priorities of Global Justice,” p. 43. of the owners and managers whose actions are the most immediate cause. None of these more distant agents can act alone to improve working conditions, however. Instead they must act collectively. Thus taking responsibility for distant sweatshop conditions involves recognizing a shared responsibility, persuading others that they share it as well, and organizing forms of collective action designed to change the incentive structures, alter the constraints, or shift the distribution of benefits in continuing to buy and sell goods manufactured by superexploited workers. IV. REASONING ABOUT POLITICAL RESPONSIBILITY Some people might object to the conception of political responsibility I have outlined on the grounds that it seems to make nearly everyone responsible for nearly everything. Most of us participate in a number of structural processes that arguably have disadvantaging, harmful or unjust consequences for some people in virtue of our jobs, the market choices we make, or other activities. Surely it is asking too much, the objection runs, for each of us to worry about all these modes of participating in structures and how we might adjust our lives and relation to others so as to reduce their unjust effects. Our relation to many of these structural processes is so diffuse, and the possibility that our own action can effect a change in outcomes is often so remote, that it is more reasonable to limit our moral concern to matters where we stand in direct relation to others and can see clearly the effect of our action on them. Before attempting to quell this fear that accepting a concept of political responsibility makes everyone equally responsible for all injustices, let me dwell for a moment on this anxiety. Part of the purpose for noticing structural injustice and theorizing responsibility in relation to it is precisely to question the common intuition that the moral claims of justice ought not to be too demanding on individuals. Many philosophers and citizens reject as unreasonable moral arguments whose conclusions would require decent law-abiding persons to give up very much time, energy, or resources in the effort to right wrongs. Within a different paradigm of moral responsibility, however, which I will call existentialist, the claims of justice unavoidably create anxiety. Yes, there are more and greater needs, harms, and social problems than we feel our puny efforts can respond to. Just because we might find overwhelming the objective problems that call for responsibility and may feel ourselves inadequate to this call is not a reason to trim down moral claims to a more emotionally manageable size. I argued above that the structural injustices for which we share responsibility occur through ongoing and normally accepted institutional relations and actions. Taking political responsibility thus often entails bringing what is normal and acceptable into question, to the extent that it produces or reproduces injustice. As Liam Murphy argues, so long as the society in which we live is far from the ideal of justice, moral demands on individuals will be rather stringent and RESPONSIBILITY & GLOBAL LABOR JUSTICE 383 perhaps difficult to meet. They do not amount to every individual taking on the personal burden of righting all wrongs, however, which is unreasonable, but persons jointly working to make better institutions.24 If the motive for the objection is not to reduce the idea of political responsibility to absurdity, but rather to ask how a person should reason about his or her own action in the face of structural injustice, then the question is reasonable. While I cannot answer the question adequately in the space remaining in this essay, I will indicate some parameters for reasoning about a particular agent’s responsibility in relation to structural injustice. Robert Goodin theorizes a conception of social responsibility which attends more to outcomes than to the causal production of harms. In answer to the question, how then do agents know what are their responsibilities, he proposes a notion of task responsibility. A person’s position in an institution or the relationship in which he or she stands with others implies certain duties to see to it that specific ends come about; the performer of a task has some discretion about how these responsibilities will be discharged, as long as these ends are achieved. If other people do not discharge their responsibilities, moreover, he or she may have responsibilities to try to make up for their laxity from their own position, even though there may be no extra reward for doing so.25 This idea of task responsibility may be a good starting point for responding to the above stated fear that political responsibility makes everyone responsible for everything. A concept of task responsibility highlights the fact that many people share responsibility for producing acceptable outcomes. There is thus a division of labor in political responsibility; each of us must look to our own institutional positions, skills and capacities, and the other responsibilities that come to us, to assess our tasks that will most effectively coordinate with others to help bring about more just outcomes. If task responsibility refers to the way existing institutions assign responsibilities to persons, however, this concept will often fall short as a guide to reasoning about action in relation to structural injustice. For one of the causes of structural injustices is the way at least some institutions assign tasks. A spokeswoman for a major retailer’s job is to issue statements of concern about sweatshop working conditions which deflect responsibility onto faraway subcontractors. A lawyer’s job in the same company is to prepare and review documents that ensure that the multiple contractual relationships the retailer has conform to law in every jurisdiction under which they fall. The sales clerk’s job in an outlet store that sells the company’s clothes is to flatter me when I try on the clothes. By hypothesis here, the problem is not that people are failing in the performance of their tasks; on the contrary, they are doing their jobs very well. The problem is the way that the institutions are defined, their power, purposes 384 IRIS MARION YOUNG 24Liam B. Murphy, Moral Demands in Nonideal Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000). 25Robert Goodin, “Apportioning responsibilities,” Utilitarianism as a Public Philosophy, pp. 100–18. and interactions with one another, as well as how they define tasks to fulfill those purposes. While the performance of certain institutionally defined tasks contributes to the perpetuation of injustice, at the same time there may be tasks that could be performed for which there is no place in existing institutions. It is no one’s job to protect workers who try to organize a union in their hidden production facility, no official well-resourced government or international agency has assigned members of its staff the task of reducing the perceived need for export processing zones or changing incentives for small factory owners in the developing world. Political responsibility in respect to structural injustice, in other words, often requires transforming institutions and the tasks they assign. This is everyone’s task and no one’s in particular. Thus we may have arrived again at the question, given that there are many institutional situations that should be transformed in order to further social justice, how should individuals think about their own responsibilities? One parameter of thinking here refers to the degree of injustice. Where basic rights are violated in a widespread fashion over a long term, world citizens have greater responsibility to take action directed at redress than for lesser injustices. The anti-sweatshop movement has succeeded in promoting widespread public discussion of labor conditions precisely because the working conditions it exposes are both egregious, widespread, and predictable. Approaching such structural injustice, we can appeal not to pre-assigned tasks that people have, but rather to their institutional or social position. What might be required from one’s position is doing something different from or additional to the tasks normally assigned to that position, but different persons nevertheless stand in differing positions in structures that produce unjust outcomes, which afford them different opportunities and capacities for influencing those outcomes. I suggest that persons can reason about their action in relation to structural injustice along parameters of connection, power, and privilege. Connection – Earlier I argued that moral agents have responsibilities in relation to any and all of those whose participation in institutions one assumes by one’s own actions. This conclusion generates the problem now under discussion, because most of us are connected to too many people mediated by too many institutions to be able to take active responsibility in respect to all of them. One way to prioritize among these is to give specificity to some connections that are easier to discern as implicating institutions in which one is directly involved. Tracing particular connection between my own action locales – my workplace, my city, my church – and distant strangers potentially affected by or related to the activities of these institutions helps to de-reify the anonymous structural processes that mediate between us. The anti-sweatshop movement has had some success in reducing the anonymity of market processes by demanding that universities and other bulk consumers, as well as large retailers, identify the RESPONSIBILITY & GLOBAL LABOR JUSTICE 385 sites where particular items sold in particular places to which they are connected are manufactured. Giving such pragmatic priority to connections that I can discern between my institutional participation and faraway others carries the danger, however, that severe injustice will be ignored because people have not seen, or have chosen not to see, this sort of connection between themselves and this injustice. Recognizing the importance of connection in locating responsibility, some people decide that the way to exercise this responsibility is by trying to disconnect. They choose not to buy certain products or brands, for example, because they have reason to think that they are manufactured under unjust conditions. Where such boycott is individual it has no effect on those conditions, however. It is nearly impossible in the contemporary world for a person to remove herself from implication through her actions in structures that produce injustice. To the extent that this implication is a ground of political responsibility, then, the responsibility cannot be removed by attempts at withdrawal; it can only be taken up. Organized boycotts involving masses of people can be one effective means of exercising political responsibility. Power – A person’s position in structural processes usually carries different degrees of potential or actual power or influence over the processes that produce the outcomes. Organizations and institutions, moreover, vary in their power and ability to influence structural processes. Some of the large major clothing retailers, for example, such as Benetton, Gap, or Guess?, have built transnational systems not only of retail outlets, but directly contract with small manufacturers. Because of the size, reach and relative influence of such organizations, it makes sense to expect major decision-makers in them to take responsibility for working conditions.26 The anti-sweatshop movement recognizes this criterion of power or influence often by targeting its actions on corporate or regulatory bodies arguably with power to change structural processes. The power and influence parameter for reasoning suggests that where individuals and organizations do not have sufficient energy and resources to respond to all structural injustices to which they are connected, they should focus on those where they have more capacity to influence structural processes. More powerful individuals and institutions, of course, often have more interest in perpetuation of the status quo than change in the processes and their outcomes. For this reason individuals and organizations with relatively less power but some ability to influence the powerful individuals and institutions can take responsibility actively to pressure the more powerful to take responsibility for change. 386 IRIS MARION YOUNG 26Major retail firms have increasingly gained control over a vertically integrated global apparel industry. See Bonacich and Appelbaum, Behind the Label, ch. 3; Rosen, Making Sweatshops, chs 10 and 11. Some lawyers argue for a legal strategy that would extend liability for violations of labor standards to the manufacturer who contracts out work, and not only to the contractor. See Leo L. Lam, “Designer duty: extending liability to manufacturers for violations of labor standards in garment industry sweatshops,” University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 141 (1992), 623–67. Such a strategy must be pursued within a single legal system, of course, and cannot cross jurisdictions between, say, Thailand and the United States. Privilege – Where there are structural injustices, these usually produce not only victims of injustice, but persons who acquire relative privileges by virtue of the structures. Most who occupy positions of power within mediated institutions or processes that harm some people or make them vulnerable to harm also derive privileges from this power. In most situations of structural injustice, there are relatively privileged persons who have relatively little power as individuals in their institutional positions. North American college students or European office workers who buy shirts or shoes made under sweatshop conditions have little power by virtue of their position. They are privileged, however, both in relation to sweatshop workers and to many other people in the world. Persons who benefit relatively from structural inequalities have special moral responsibilities to contribute to organized efforts to correct them, not because they are to blame for them, but because they have more resources and are able to adapt to changed circumstances without suffering serious deprivation. From this point that privilege generates special responsibilities, however, it does not follow that victims of injustice do not share responsibility for contributing to the alteration of the circumstances that constrain their options. On the contrary. I pointed out earlier that one difference between a liability model of responsibility and the concept of political responsibility consists precisely in that those who suffer injustice share responsibility for helping to bring about change. Thus in the example of sweatshops, the specific position of the workers carries unique responsibilities. Their conditions are likely to improve only if they organize to demand and monitor such improvement. Victims of injustice, however, usually can only succeed in their own efforts to change the structural conditions of injustice if others in a position to support them take responsibility to do so. Political responsibility, I have argued above, is necessarily a shared responsibility both because the injustices that call for redress are the product of the mediated actions of many, and thus because they can only be rectified through collective action. For most such injustices, the goal is to change structural processes by reforming institutions or creating new ones that will better regulate the process to prevent harmful outcomes. Thus a final consideration in reasoning about where a person might put her practical energies in taking political responsibility involves coordination with others to achieve such change. Just as a person can make almost no difference by trying to disconnect from the processes, so an individual can rarely decide to act alone or with just a few other people to change it. Thus sometimes the fact that there is a promising movement to join can be a reason to give priority to some issues over others. Movements always need beginnings, of course; so in the absence of coordinated action involving significant numbers of people, but where other considerations ought to make a particular issue of high priority, a few individuals can try to persuade others of its importance and enjoin them to become organized. Like some other forms of responsibility, political responsibility is open about what actions count as discharging it. While in this paper I have endorsed the RESPONSIBILITY & GLOBAL LABOR JUSTICE 387 claims of the anti-sweatshop movement that apparel manufacturers, institutional purchasers of apparel, and individual consumers have responsibilities toward faraway workers who produce these goods, I have said nothing about what ought to be done to improve those conditions structurally. The anti- sweatshop movement has had some significant successes in its short life, not only in raising consciousness and motivating some people and institutions to assume responsibility, but also in increasing transparency of the connections among factories and firms in the industry and in supporting unions of affected workers. Nevertheless, there are significant disagreements both within and outside the movement about whether some tactics do more harm than good and thus about what are the best ways in the long run to encourage and enforce decent working conditions.27 V. CONCLUSION The main purpose of this essay has been to begin an answer to the question: how should agents think about responsibility in relation to structural social injustice? I have proposed a concept of political responsibility which is distinct from a liability model of responsibility in five respects. (1) Unlike responsibility as liability, political responsibility does not isolate some responsibility parties in order to absolve others. (2) Whereas blame or liability seeks remedy for a deviation from an acceptable norm, usually by an event that has reached a terminus, with political responsibility we are concerned with structural causes of injustice that are normal and ongoing. (3) Political responsibility is more forward-looking than backward-looking. (4) What it means to take up or assign political responsibility is more open and discretionary than what it means to hold an agent blameworthy or liable. (5) An agent shares political responsibility with others whose actions contribute to the structural processes that produce injustice. I have elaborated this concept of political responsibility through the example of the apparel industry and the social movement seeking changes in working conditions in it for at least two reasons. This example exhibits structural injustice where some of the social positions in the structure are fairly easy to identify. Because in this case the structures cross nations and boundaries, moreover, it well illustrates that the scope of issues of justice corresponding to political responsibility derives not from the boundaries of a state or political jurisdiction, but from the connections generated by the structural processes. Where this scope is beyond existing regulatory and political institutions, there may be need to construct some to correspond to that scope. While in this essay I have focused on political responsibility for labor conditions in a global industry, my claim is that the concept is generalizable and applies to any structural social injustice. 388 IRIS MARION YOUNG 27For one set of debates, see Archon Fung, Dara O’Rourke, and Charles Sabel, eds, Can We Put an End to Sweatshops? (Boston: Beacon Press, 2001). work_hlqndjyq65d2dh2kwnyyl2khoe ---- Ethics & Global Politics: Vol 14, No 1 Log in  |  Register Cart Home All Journals Ethics & Global Politics List of Issues Volume 14, Issue 1 Ethics & Global Politics An open access journal Publishes research on ethics and global politics, exploring environmental protection, policy development, poverty, technology and knowledge, migration and more. Search in: This Journal Anywhere Advanced search Submit an article New content alerts RSS Citation search Citation search Current issue Browse list of issues Explore Top About this journal Journal metrics Aims and scope Instructions for authors Journal information Editorial board News & offers Editorial policies Latest articles See all volumes and issues Volume 14, 2021 Vol 13, 2020 Vol 12, 2019 Vol 11, 2018 Vol 10, 2017 Vol 9, 2016 Vol 8, 2015 Vol 7, 2014 Vol 6, 2013 Vol 5, 2012-2013 Vol 4, 2011 Vol 3, 2010 Vol 2, 2009 Vol 1, 2008 Login or register to access this feature Have an account? Login nowDon't have an account? Register for free Register a free Taylor & Francis Online account today to boost your research and gain these benefits: Download multiple PDFs directly from your searches and from tables of contents Easy remote access to your institution's subscriptions on any device, from any location Save your searches and schedule alerts to send you new results Choose new content alerts to be informed about new research of interest to you Export your search results into a .csv file to support your research Register now or learn more Download citations Choose format RIS (ProCit, Reference Manager) BibTeX RefWorks Direct Export Download citations Download citations Download PDFs Browse by section (All) Display order (Default) Published online date Page number Section A-Z Most read Most cited Ethics & Global Politics, Volume 14, Issue 1 (2021) Issue In Progress Original Article Article What Kind of Functionings Matter for Global Justice for Children? Gottfried Schweiger Article: 1873576 Published online: 19 Jan 2021 Abstract | Full Text | References | PDF (318 KB) | Permissions  610Views 0CrossRef citations Altmetric Review Article review article Beyond lockdown? The ethics of global movement in a new era Guy Aitchison Published online: 04 Mar 2021 Abstract | Full Text | References | PDF (300 KB) | Permissions  563Views 0CrossRef citations Altmetric Explore Most read articles Most cited articles Multimedia Information for Authors Editors Librarians Societies Open access Overview Open journals Open Select Cogent OA Dove Medical Press F1000Research Help and info Help & contact Newsroom Commercial services Advertising information All journals Books Keep up to date Register to receive personalised research and resources by email Sign me up Taylor and Francis Group Facebook page Taylor and Francis Group Twitter page Taylor and Francis Group Linkedin page Taylor and Francis Group Youtube page Taylor and Francis Group Weibo page Copyright © 2021 Informa UK Limited Privacy policy Cookies Terms & conditions Accessibility Registered in England & Wales No. 3099067 5 Howick Place | London | SW1P 1WG Accept We use cookies to improve your website experience. To learn about our use of cookies and how you can manage your cookie settings, please see our Cookie Policy. By closing this message, you are consenting to our use of cookies. work_hlrxo2wnxzamxmemlxjbnsvt2a ---- S1742058X1600014X.indd 221 Du Bois Review, 13:2 (2016) 221– 236 . © 2016 Hutchins Center for African and African American Research 1742-058X/16 $15.00 doi:10.1017/S1742058X1600014X TOWARD A CRITICAL ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE STUDIES Black Lives Matter as an Environmental Justice Challenge David N. Pellow Department of Environmental Studies , University of California , Santa Barbara Abstract In this paper I expand upon the recent use of the term “Critical Environmental Justice Studies.” This concept is meant to capture new developments in Environmental Justice (EJ) Studies that question assumptions and gaps in earlier work in the field. Because this direction in scholarship is still in its formative stages, I take this opportunity to offer some guidance on what Critical Environmental Justice (CEJ) Studies might look like and what it could mean for theorizing the relationship between race (along with multiple additional social categories) and the environment. I do so by (1) adopting a multi-disciplinary approach that draws on several bodies of literature, including critical race theory, political ecology, ecofeminist theory, and anarchist theory, and (2) focusing on the case of Black Lives Matter and the problem of state violence. Keywords: Environmental Justice , Black Lives Matter , State Violence , Racism , Speciesism , Scale , Expendability , Indispensability INTRODUCTION Black Lives Matter (BLM) is a social movement centered on the problem of state- sanctioned racist violence. The movement began as a response to the acquittal of George Zimmerman, a man who killed Trayvon Martin, a seventeen-year old African American boy in Sanford, Florida, in 2012. From that moment on, social media, mainstream media, and the Black Lives Matter movement would routinely inten- sify the national focus on racialized state-sanctioned violence when yet another video or testimony surfaced featuring an African American being shot, beaten, choked, and/or killed by police or White vigilantes. The role of social media tech- nology was pivotal. As one writer put it, “Social media could serve as a source of live, raw information. It could summon people to the streets and coordinate their movements in real time. And it could swiftly push back against spurious media narratives . . .” (Bijan 2015 ). BLM co-founder Alicia Garza explained what the movement stands for: “Black Lives Matter is an ideological and political intervention in a world where Black lives are systematically and intentionally targeted for demise. It is an affirmation of Black at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X https://www.cambridge.org/core David N. Pellow 222 DU BOIS REVIEW: SOCIAL SCIENCE RESEARCH ON RACE 13:2, 2016 folks’ contributions to this society, our humanity, and our resilience in the face of deadly oppression” (Garza 2014 ). In this paper, I draw links between what I view as the most important insights and questions that emerge from the Black Lives Matter movement and the strug- gle against environmental racism. This is a connection that many scholars might not make at first glance because police brutality and environmental politics would appear to be only tangentially related, but I argue they are in fact closely intertwined and that we must explore their myriad connections in order to excavate the roots of racist violence no matter the form it takes. The questions I explore here include: How can Black Lives Matter’s emphasis on police violence against African American communities inform our understanding of the scourge of ecological burdens facing those same communities? Conversely, what can the violation of Black bodies and spaces by ecologically destructive agents produced by states and corporations tell us about the violation of those same bodies by police and law enforcement agents? I find that a “first-” and “second-generation” Environmental Justice Studies frame- work can assist in this effort, but can only take us so far. Therefore, I propose that a Critical Environmental Justice Studies framework can more fully address these pressing concerns. ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE STUDIES The Environmental Justice (EJ) movement is composed of people from communities of color, indigenous communities, and working-class communities who are focused on combating environmental injustice—the disproportionate burden of environmental harm facing these populations. For the EJ movement, social justice is inseparable from environmental protection. In the early 1970s, researchers in the United States found strong correlations between social class status and air quality in the United States. As a result of social movement activism, however, the focus began to broaden from social class to race and from air pollution to a range of environmental hazards (Pulido 1996 ; Walker 2010 ). For example, in 1982, hundreds of civil rights leaders and community activists protested a toxic waste dump in the majority African American community of Warren County, North Carolina. That action sparked the discourse of environmental rac- ism and the growth of Environmental Justice Studies, and since that time, scholars and other researchers have documented the reach of environmental racism/inequality in the United States and around the globe, as well as the social movement that has emerged to highlight and challenge this phenomenon (Bullard 2000 ; Cole and Foster, 2000 ; Pellow and Brulle, 2005 ). Thus, hundreds of studies have documented that people of color, people of lower socioeconomic status, indigenous and immigrant populations, and other marginalized communities are disproportionately affected by ecologically harmful infrastructures, such as landfills, mines, incinerators, polluting factories, and destructive transportation systems, as well as by the negative consequences of ecologically harmful practices, such as climate change/disruption and pesticide exposure (Ringquist 2005 ). Much of this work has documented the troubling depths and breadth of environmental injustice’s impact on the lives of people—including public health and mental health effects—and on how these communities make meaning out of these assaults while organizing for environmental justice. And while EJ Studies may have earlier focused on the United States, scholars are also documenting environmental inequalities and EJ move- ments’ responses to them around the globe (Agyeman et al., 2010 ; Pellow 2007 ; at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X https://www.cambridge.org/core Critical Environmental Justice Studies DU BOIS REVIEW: SOCIAL SCIENCE RESEARCH ON RACE 13:2, 2016 223 Roberts and Parks, 2006 ). A small but growing group of researchers—including and especially environmental humanities scholars—have focused on the ways that gender, sexuality, citizenship, indigeneity, and nation shape the terrain of eco- logical inequalities, but those areas of scholarship remain in need of further devel- opment (Adamson 2011 ; Bell 2013 ; Buckingham and Kulcur, 2010 ; Gaard 2004 ; Smith 2005 ). TOWARD A CRITICAL ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE STUDIES Recent scholarship divides EJ Studies into two phases: (1) the “first-generation,” which was focused primarily on documenting environmental inequality through the lens of race and class; and (2) “second-generation” studies that extend beyond questions of distribution to incorporate a deeper consideration of theory and the ways that gender, sexuality, and other categories of difference shape EJ struggles (Buckingham and Kulcur, 2010 ; Walker 2010 ). In our book Power, Justice, and the Environment , Robert Brulle and I used the term “Critical Environmental Justice Studies” (Pellow and Brulle, 2005 ), which has since been adopted by other scholars working to expand the academic field and politics of environmental justice (Adamson 2011 ; Holifield et al., 2010 ). This concept is meant to build on recent scholarship in EJ Studies— “second-generation” writings—that questions assumptions and gaps in earlier work in the field by embracing interdisciplinarity and methodologies and epistemologies including and beyond the social sciences. As this direction in scholarship is still in its formative stages, I take this opportunity to offer some guidance for what a Critical EJ Studies might look like. Critical EJ (CEJ) Studies is a perspective intended to address a number of limita- tions and tensions within EJ Studies. These include, for example: (1) questions con- cerning the degree to which scholars should place emphasis on one or more social categories of difference (e.g., race, class, gender, sexuality, species, etc.) versus a focus on multiple forms of inequality; (2) the extent to which scholars studying EJ issues should focus on single-scale versus multi-scalar analyses of the causes, consequences, and possible resolutions of EJ struggles; (3) the degree to which various forms of social inequality and power—including state power—are viewed as entrenched and embed- ded in society; and (4) the largely unexamined question of the expendability of human and non-human populations facing socioecological threats from states, industries, and other political economic forces. On the first point above, EJ scholars have a tendency to focus on only one or two forms of social inequality in studies of environmental injustice. For example, some scholars continue to debate the relative importance of race versus class in terms of which category is most important with respect to the distribution of environmental hazards, while only a small group of scholars have explored the role of gender and sexuality in EJ Studies (Buckingham and Kulcur, 2010 ; Smith 2005 ). Moreover, the key social category species remains, at best, at the margins of the field of EJ Studies, despite the fact that, generally, when and where humans suffer from environmental inequalities, so does the more-than-human world (and vice versa) and often as a result of ideological frameworks that link marginalized humans to “nature.” My point here is that since multiple forms of inequality drive and characterize the experi- ence of environmental injustice, the field would do well to expand in that direc- tion. Thus CEJ Studies brings greater attention to how multiple social categories of difference are entangled in the production of environmental injustice, from race, gender, sexuality, ability, and class to species, which would attend to the at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X https://www.cambridge.org/core David N. Pellow 224 DU BOIS REVIEW: SOCIAL SCIENCE RESEARCH ON RACE 13:2, 2016 ways that both the human and the more-than-human world are impacted by and respond to environmental injustice. With respect to the second point above concerning scale , the EJ Studies literature tends to be characterized by research at one scale or another, rather than a multi-scalar approach. In other words, most researchers focus on the local, regional, national, or sometimes transnational or global scale, but few studies attempt to grasp how EJ struggles function at multiple scales, from the cellular and bodily level to the global level and back (Herod 2011 ; Sze 2016 ). Some scholars have addressed this important question by exploring cases in which pollutants produced in one part of the world travel across national borders and impact human and ecological health in another hemisphere (Sze 2006 ). Scale is of critical importance because it allows us to under- stand how environmental injustices are facilitated by decision-makers who behave as if sites where hazards are produced “out of sight and out of mind” are somehow irrel- evant to the health of people and ecosystems at the original sites of decision-making power and consumption. Attention to scale also assists us in observing how social movement responses to environmental injustices draw on spatial frameworks, networks, and knowledge to make the connections between hazards in one place and harm in another. CEJ Studies thus advocates multi-scalar methodological and theoretical approaches to studying EJ issues in order to better comprehend the complex spatial and temporal causes, consequences, and possible resolutions of EJ struggles. Regarding the third point above—the degree to which various forms of inequality and power are viewed as entrenched in society—this concern stems from my conclu- sion that the vision of change articulated by EJ Studies scholars and most EJ activ- ists generally looks to the state and capital to accommodate demands via legislation, institutional reforms, and other policy concessions. The concern here is that such an approach leaves intact the very power structures that produced environmental injus- tice in the first place. Yes, it names those institutions and structures as sources of the problems and seeks to reform them, but by working in collaboration with those entities, such efforts ultimately risk reinforcing their legitimacy. CEJ Studies urges a deeper grasp of the entrenched and embedded character of social inequality—including speciesism and state power—in society and therefore a reckoning with the need for transforma- tive (rather than primarily reformist) approaches to realize environmental justice. In other words, Critical EJ Studies seeks to push our analyses and actions beyond the human, the state, and capital via a broad anti-authoritarian perspective. Regarding the fourth point above, EJ Studies suggests that various marginalized human populations are treated—if not viewed—as inferior, and less valuable, to society than others. This point is largely undertheorized in the literature (Mills 2001 ; Pulido 1996 ). Critical EJ Studies makes this theme explicit by arguing that these populations are marked for erasure and early death, and that ideological and institutional other- ing is linked to the more-than-human world as well. Moreover, CEJ counters that dominant perspective with a framework that contends that these threatened bodies, populations, and spaces are indispensable to building socially and environmentally just and resilient futures for us all. The above constitute what I call the four pillars of CEJ Studies. CEJ Studies draws from the work of scholars across numerous fields that only periodically inter- sect, such as Environmental Justice Studies (Adamson 2011 ; Bell 2013 ; Bullard 2000 ; Cole and Foster, 2000 ), Critical Race Theory (Goldberg 2002 ), Critical Race Feminism (Hong 2006 ; Smith 2005 ), Ethnic Studies (Márquez 2014 ), Gender and Sexuality Studies and Ecofeminism (Buckingham and Kulcur, 2010 ; Gaard 2004 ), Political Ecology (Bennett 2009 ), and Anti-Authoritarian/Anarchist Theory (Scott 2010 ; Smith 2011 ). Furthermore, CEJ Studies is interdisciplinary, multi-methodological, and at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X https://www.cambridge.org/core Critical Environmental Justice Studies DU BOIS REVIEW: SOCIAL SCIENCE RESEARCH ON RACE 13:2, 2016 225 is activist-scholar inspired in that it seeks to bridge and blur the boundaries and borders between the academy and community, theory and practice, analysis and action. Critical EJ Studies is only intended to be one of many possible approaches to environmental justice scholarship and action. It is neither prescriptive, nor is it a declaration of where the field should be headed. In the following sections, I apply a CEJ Studies framework to the Black Lives Matter movement to demonstrate the importance of encouraging scholars and activists to think through linkages across theory and social change politics that might not usually emerge from “traditional” EJ Studies or from within many social change movements. CRITICAL EJ STUDIES AND BLACK LIVES MATTER In order to examine Black Lives Matter as a CEJ case study, I gathered data from the BLM website, archives, and social media, as well as major essays published in national and international media outlets by BLM advocates and supporters. This selection of data is not intended to be strictly representative, but rather, as a purposive sample it speaks to the core BLM frames and the four pillars of CEJ Studies. The First Pillar: Intersectionality and the Racial Discourse of Animality CEJ Studies recognizes that social inequality and oppression in all forms intersect and that members of the more-than-human world are subjects of oppression and agents of social change. Black Lives Matter is a social movement organized primarily around the social category of race, but extends the analysis to multiple categories of difference, reflecting an emphasis on intersectionality . Intersectionality is a concept intended to explain the ways that many identities and social categories work together to produce advantages and disadvantages across bodies and space, and that inequalities do not act independently of one another (Collins 2008 ; Hong 2006 ). The founders of BLM present a deeply intersectional approach to the problem of devalued Black life that is inclusive of class, gender, sexuality, immigration status, citizenship, age, ability, and other differences and social categories. All three founders of BLM are women of color. One of them—Alicia Garza—identifies as a queer woman of color, while another—Opal Tometi—is the daughter of Nigerian immigrants and works for an organization focused on the human rights of Black immigrants. The third founder—Patrisse Cullors—who also identifies as queer, organizes support for incar- cerated persons and their families, with a focus on mental health. Thus their political and professional work itself is a study in intersectional theory and practice. As BLM co-founder Alicia Garza writes, “Black Lives Matter affirms the lives of Black queer and trans folks, disabled folks, Black-undocumented folks, folks with records, women, and all Black lives along the gender spectrum” (Garza 2014 ). Critical EJ Studies speaks to the ways in which various social categories of dif- ference work to place particular bodies at risk of exclusion, marginalization, erasure, discrimination, violence, and othering. These insights are important for building an understanding of the ways that intra-human inequality and oppressions function and how they intersect with human-nonhuman oppression. As David Nibert and Michael Fox put it, “[T]he oppression of various devalued groups in human societies is not independent and unrelated; rather, the arrangements that lead to various forms of oppression are integrated in such a way that the exploitation of one group frequently augments and compounds the mistreatment of others” (Nibert and Fox, 2002 , p. 13). “Various devalued groups in human societies” frequently include women, immigrants, at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X https://www.cambridge.org/core David N. Pellow 226 DU BOIS REVIEW: SOCIAL SCIENCE RESEARCH ON RACE 13:2, 2016 LGBTQ persons, people of color, indigenous peoples, disabled persons, the elderly, low-income people, and nonhuman species. And while the experiences of these groups are qualitatively distinct (i.e., not equivalent), the logic of domination and othering as practiced by more powerful groups, the state, and capital provides the common thread of intersectionality through each of their oppressions. Law enforcement personnel routinely engage in violent acts against humans and nonhumans, even when no threat is evident, thus revealing the ways that state violence produces intersecting oppressions. A 2015 Baltimore Sun investigation of the Baltimore, Maryland Police Department (the same town where Freddie Gray was murdered), detailed numerous incidents in which vulnerable people and nonhumans were the sub- jects of brutal and sometimes lethal force at the hands of police in that city. The report notes that young African American males were the targets of such violence, and so were elderly people, women, children, and nonhuman animals (Friedersdorf 2015 ). The report discusses, for example, the use of a dead rat to intimidate a police officer working on a police brutality case and the murder of a dog by an officer to intimidate his girlfriend. The Baltimore Sun investigation appears to reflect what scholarly studies have long revealed: that there is a well-documented link between the use of violence against nonhuman animals and efforts to exert control over other humans, whether in the destruction of livestock and other food sources during wartime and conquests or through domestic violence directed primarily at women, children, and nonhuman companion animals or pets (Adams 2010 ; Ascione 1997 ; Smits 1994 ). This brings us to what I call the racial discourse of animality , a term meant to capture the language that people use to describe human behavior using nonhuman references and analogies, signaling a set of assumptions surrounding what we view as acceptable “human” versus nonhuman behavior and how different bodies are valued. It reveals the means through which we discuss race, racism, and racial politics in more-than-human terms, as a way of defining the limits and boundaries of the human. This discourse is common in discussions around racial politics and flared up many times around BLM protests against police brutality. What is fascinating is that people on all sides of the issues—activists, lawyers, and agents of the state—use this language. In other words, people deploy the racial discourse of animality in the service of White supremacy and in the service of racial justice. Consider the following examples: Lesley McSpadden, the mother of Michael Brown (an African American teenager killed by a police officer in Ferguson, Missouri) spoke to reporters at a public dem- onstration to call attention to the tragedy of her son’s death. She spoke to the bleak outlook of young African Americans facing police brutality: “You took my son away from me! You know how hard it was for me to get him to stay in school and gradu- ate? You know how many Black men graduate? Not many! Because you bring them down to this type of level where they feel they don’t got nothing to live for anyway!” While other protesters around McSpadden peacefully raised their hands in symbolic surrender, a police officer’s voice was heard and recorded yelling at them, calling them “animals” (Fantz et al., 2014 ). In early 2015, Freddie Gray, a twenty-five year old African American man was taken into police custody in Baltimore, Maryland, and, in the process, incurred severe spinal cord and neck injuries and died shortly afterward, sparking nationwide protests. In Baltimore, the protests, led by African Americans and many supporters of the BLM movement, were mainly peaceful but were marred by property destruction, looting, and a number of police officers being injured. Many Whites took to social media— including Baltimore County police officer Jennifer Lynne Silver—and displayed their views on the matter referring to the people involved as “animals” and, in her words, a “disgrace to the human race” ( Change.org 2015). at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X https://www.cambridge.org/core Critical Environmental Justice Studies DU BOIS REVIEW: SOCIAL SCIENCE RESEARCH ON RACE 13:2, 2016 227 The racial discourse of animality is also used to combat racism. An article in The Guardian responded to Jennifer Silver’s epithets regarding protesters in Baltimore by arguing that police and society often treat nonhuman animals better than African Americans: But ‘animals’ is a misnomer. People—including police officers—are punished for killing or doing harm to domestic animals. Baltimore has busted dog fighting rings and sent offenders to prison for animal cruelty. In 2014, former Baltimore City police officer Alec Taylor was sentenced to a year behind bars for killing a dog. That might not seem like much, but it is longer than the sentences given to the killers of Michael Brown, Eric Garner, Trayvon Martin, Rekia Boyd, or seven-year old Aiyana Stanley-Jones (Nichols 2015 ). In the spring of 2015, a police officer shot Walter Scott, an unarmed African American man in North Charleston, South Carolina, after he fled his car during a traffic stop. Malik Shabazz, president of Black Lawyers for America and former chairman of the New Black Panther Party, appeared on “CNN Newsroom” and stated, “Black men are being killed and hunted down like deer and like dogs” (Griswold 2015 ). That same month, Democratic Congressman Hank Johnson of Georgia took to the floor of the House of Representatives to urge his colleagues to confront police brutality. Drawing on a phrase usually reserved for hunting nonhuman animals, he stated, “It feels like open season on Black men in America” (Griswold 2015 , emphasis added). In these last examples, references to nonhumans are used to communicate the sentiment that African Americans—like all human beings, presumably—should not be treated like nonhuman animals. The assumption here is also problematic because it is speciesist in that it implies that it is acceptable to wantonly hunt and slaughter nonhumans, even if the primary aim is to counter racist violence. My point is that we cannot understand racist violence, and the way we think, talk, and enact it, with- out paying attention to the relationship between humans and nonhumans, as these examples illustrate. Finally, the role of agency is key to the first pillar of CEJ, since African Americans and other marginalized populations are not just the targets of oppression but also regularly resist their subjugation. While traditional elements of what sociologists call “resource mobilization” (Morris 1984 ) are on full display with the Black Lives Matter movement—including the mobilization of human bodies, ideas, words, discourses, tactics, and strategies in protest—it is also the case that the urban built environment, information technology, and other forms of more-than-human objects and natures are also integral to that agency and therefore central to making this vision and practice of social change possible (Bennett 2009 ). The Second Pillar: Scale, Race, and Difference CEJ Studies embraces multi-scalar methodological and theoretical approaches in order to better comprehend the complex spatial and temporal causes, consequences, and possible resolutions of EJ struggles. Scale is deeply racialized, gendered, and classed. The impacts of climate change offer a telling example of how environmental racism reflects this fact. While the conclusions of climate scientists are remarkably clear that anthropogenic climate change is occurring at a dramatic pace and with increasing intensity, this is also happening unevenly, with people of color, the poor, indigenous peoples, peoples of at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X https://www.cambridge.org/core David N. Pellow 228 DU BOIS REVIEW: SOCIAL SCIENCE RESEARCH ON RACE 13:2, 2016 the global South, and women suffering the most (Harlan et al., 2015 ). Thus, while climate change matters for all of us, it impacts people and nonhumans with dif- ferent levels of intensity. If one only pays attention to the global scale, it appears that the worst effects of climate change are not yet upon us. But if one examines what is occurring in neighborhoods, barrios , indigenous peoples’ lands, and much of the global South, the picture is quite different because the impacts are extensive and ongoing. As Keith Ellison and Van Jones ( 2015 ) put it, “[O]ur kids are being poisoned by the air they breathe. Environmental injustices are taking Black lives— that’s why our fight for equality has to include climate and environmental justice too.” Social cognition studies find that “implicit bias” among White research sub- jects results in perceiving threats to their wellbeing when they see Black and Brown people when no such threat exists (Kang 2005 ). While this research is highly con- sequential for everyday microsociological interactions across the racial spectrum (especially in the case of gun violence in the name of White “self defense”), it has major macrosociological implications as well. Therefore I find that implicit bias is useful for thinking more deeply about the intersection of race and scale. In other words, if these studies find that people of color are implicitly viewed as threaten- ing, then their presence is perceived to be much larger in the social-cognitive terrain of Whites. Thus race and scale intertwine to reveal also that when Black people respond to racism (whether by police or via environmental racism), their actions may be viewed as a threat that is disproportionate and outsized. We can see this, for example, in the militarized response by police departments when interacting with the Black Lives Matter movement. Many supporters of the Black Lives Matter movement, and even military veterans, decried these practices when disturbing images of police and pro- testers clashing in Ferguson, Missouri, in response to the police killing of Michael Brown, seemed to be indistinguishable from media images of civilians being repressed by an occupying military force in some far away land. This fact begs for a scalar analy- sis that links militarized oppression of African Americans to the U.S. military’s treat- ment of people of color elsewhere in the world—in Afghanistan, Iraq, Syria, Pakistan, Yemen, Palestine, and many other nations where the United States uses military force directly or by proxy to protect its interests. This is also an environmental justice issue because the U.S. military is one of the largest sources of pollution on earth (Nazaryan 2014 ) and because militarism and masculinist politics tend to go hand in hand and both tend to result in socially and ecologically harmful practices. Finally, BLM’s work speaks to the myriad ways that scale can be thought of and articulated temporally . In fact, the entire point of the BLM movement is, in some ways, an intervention to remind us that blatant acts of anti-Black violence are not a thing of the past and are still quite rampant in what some observers had hoped would be a “postracial” era. BLM co-founder Alicia Garza uses time as an indicator of the inter- section of race, sexuality, and scale’s intersections, but does so linking history to an imagined future: But what I can say to my child, just like my mom says to me, is that there was a time when it wasn’t OK for people to be out [about their sexuality]. There was a time when black people were being slaughtered. And I hope that the end to that story is, ‘and then we organized, and we built a vibrant international movement, and we really changed conditions for black people in this country, and for every- body.’ And I’m hoping that the story that I’m also able to tell is that our demands went beyond ‘stop killing us,’ to ensure the quality of life for everybody. And that we won that (Brydum 2015 ). at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X https://www.cambridge.org/core Critical Environmental Justice Studies DU BOIS REVIEW: SOCIAL SCIENCE RESEARCH ON RACE 13:2, 2016 229 The Third Pillar: An Anti-Statist/Anarchist Reading of BLM Social inequalities—from racism to speciesism—are not aberrations, but rather are deeply embedded in society and reinforced by state power and market systems. There- fore, the current social order stands as a fundamental obstacle to social and environ- mental justice. A logical conclusion of this observation is that social change movements may be better off thinking and acting beyond the state and capital as targets of reform and/or as reliable partners. Racism, for example, is a foundational component of the political, legal, economic, and cultural systems in the United States. African Americans, for instance, enjoy fewer rights and significantly lower social value than Whites, suffering deep economic, educa- tional, public health, and environmental inequalities; earning far less income and owning far less wealth and property than Whites; and being more likely than Whites to attend low quality, segregated schools and live in residentially segregated communities marked by financial disinvestment, a brutal occupying police force presence, and environmental racism (Bullard 2000 ; Cacho 2012 ; Gilmore 2007 ; Vargas 2010 ). Public health dispari- ties impact African Americans dramatically, as homicides, infant mortality, life expec- tancy, asthma, and a range of other illnesses and life events reveal a much lower statistical value of Black life (Williams and Collins, 1995 ). And millions of African Americans are either confined to prisons via mass incarceration or subjected to routine surveillance and control through the system of mass probation. Thus, racism is, for Black Lives Matter co-founder Alicia Garza, “a disease that this country has in our very DNA” (Garza 2015 ). In a statement posted on the Black Lives Matter website, activists contend that the current state of racist violence against African Americans is a core component of American life, a form of oppression that Blacks have consistently challenged: “Rooted in the experiences of Black people in this country who actively resist our de-humanization, #BlackLivesMatter is a call to action and a response to the virulent anti-Black racism that permeates our society” ( BlackLivesMatter.com 2016). Debates often center on whether social movements should seek to reform or trans- form the legal system. BLM is an important part of that conversation because it is a movement whose participants often embrace the state, but frequently do so in a critical fashion. For example, much of the chanting and protest calls at BLM events include demands to “prosecute the police” and implement stronger laws against hate crimes and police brutality (Furst 2016 ). 1 The BLM’s “National Demands” document reads, in part, “We will help develop a network of organizations and advocates to form a national policy specifically aimed at redressing the systemic pattern of anti-Black law enforcement violence in the U.S.” (Moore and Cullors, 2014 ). In November 2015, after a group of White supremacists shot and wounded several activists who were pro- testing the police killing of an unarmed African American man named Jamar Clark in Minneapolis, BLM released a statement declaring, “The Black Lives Matter Network urgently calls upon the Department of Justice to investigate this shooting as a hate crime” ( BlackLivesMatter.com 2015). Finally, BLM activists have regularly called for greater oversight over police and for increased presence of Black people in govern- ment decision-making bodies. For example, in the wake of numerous police killings of African Americans in recent years, the Los Angeles chapter of BLM demanded that the mayor appoint activists from the Black community to key city commissions, and a number of BLM activists are running for political office. When BLM demands inclusion in governmental bodies and invokes the language of hate crimes and terrorism, such efforts may appear to reflect the power of grass- roots movements to move state actors on important progressive issues, but it also indicates the movement’s willingness to expand troubling, controlling, authoritative, and at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X https://www.cambridge.org/core David N. Pellow 230 DU BOIS REVIEW: SOCIAL SCIENCE RESEARCH ON RACE 13:2, 2016 lethal state power. BLM is therefore not asking how we might build safe communities beyond the state, but rather how we might do so with greater state intervention. BLM co-founder Patrice Cullors’ vision of social change includes a plan to “divest from policing and divest from this prison system . . . and reinvest into poor communities, reinvest into allowing us to have access to healthy food, access to jobs, access to shelter” (Cullors 2015 ). From a pluralist perspective, states are sites where citizens and other stakeholders converge to elect representatives and make their voices heard and shape public policy (Dahl 2005 ). Departing from that view, a power elite perspective casts states as sites of power struggles, where certain interest groups tend to dominate others, setting public policy agendas and unevenly shaping life chances for members of society (Domhoff 2013 ). From Women of Color Feminist, Critical Race Theory, and Anarchist per- spectives, states are also institutions that, by definition, practice exclusion, control, and violence (in addition to their other functions) (Goldberg 2002 ; Hong 2006 ; Mills 2001 ; Scott 2010 ; Smith 2011 ). Thus, the very purpose of a state is to exert dominance over populations, resources, and territory, among other things. If Black Lives Matter was founded to challenge state-sanctioned violence then it makes sense to extend the reach of this movement’s analysis and action to the prob- lem of environmental racism. Since environmental racism is often a form of state- sanctioned violence via the harm that state agencies and state-regulated companies perpetrate in communities of color, then BLM might do well to pay greater attention to this issue. If we think of environmental racism as a form of violent control over bodies, space, and knowledge systems then we can more effectively theorize it as a form of state violence, a framework that is absent from most EJ scholarship. 2 More- over, as some BLM activists urge us to think about how to make our communities safe “beyond policing” (Tometi 2015 ), both BLM and EJ activists and scholars might begin to think about how to make our communities sites of EJ and racial justice beyond the state . In fact, the BLM movement, the EJ movement, and EJ scholarship generally look to the state and its legal systems to deliver justice and to regulate industry. Thus far, however, the track record of state-based regulation and enforcement of racial and environmental justice policies in communities of color has been abysmal (Cole and Foster, 2000 ; Gilmore 2007 ; Lombardi et al., 2015 ). The Fourth Pillar: Indispensability Critical EJ Studies centers on the concepts of racial and socioecological indispensability . In Black and Brown Solidarity ( 2014 ), John Márquez introduces the concept “racial expendability” to argue that Black and Brown bodies are, in the eyes of the state and its constituent legal system, generally viewed as criminal, deficient, threatening, and deserving of violent discipline and even obliteration. Márquez and other ethnic studies scholars contend that, in a White supremacist society, people of color are constructed as and rendered expendable (Cacho 2012 ; Márquez 2014 ; Mills 2001 ; Vargas 2010 ). Ruth Wilson Gilmore speaks to this point in her book Golden Gulag ( 2007 ), in which she argues that the massive build up of prisons to warehouse people of color in the state of California and the United States nationally was a public policy deci- sion designed to contain and control populations whose very existence is viewed as troubling. Extending this logic to the problem of environmental racism, philosopher and critical race theorist Charles Mills argues that people of African descent are con- sidered “trash” by policy makers and institutions promoting discriminatory envi- ronmental policies because these populations are associated with filth, waste, and uncleanliness in the popular imagination—thus locating pollution in their com- munities actually makes cultural common sense (Mills 2001 ). at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X https://www.cambridge.org/core Critical Environmental Justice Studies DU BOIS REVIEW: SOCIAL SCIENCE RESEARCH ON RACE 13:2, 2016 231 Critical EJ Studies builds on the work of these scholars by countering the ideology of White supremacy and human dominionism and articulating the perspective that excluded, marginalized, and othered populations, beings, and things—both human and more-than-human—must be viewed not as expendable but rather as indispensable to our collective futures. This is what I term racial indispensability (when referring to people of color) and socioecological indispensability (when referring to broader commu- nities within and across the human/more-than-human divide and their relationships to one another). Racial indispensability is intended to challenge the logic of racial expendability and is the idea that institutions, policies, and practices that support and perpetrate anti-Black racism suffer from the flawed assumption that the future of African Americans is somehow de-linked from the future of White communities. People of color are members of our society, are core participants in our social systems, and are members of our socioecological systems, and are therefore key to ensuring the contin- ued functioning, sustainability, and resilience of our society and planet. The idea of indispensability is distinct from an assimilationist perspective, which seeks to (often involuntarily and violently) incorporate “others” into one’s own vision of a society (Smith 2005 ). Rather, indispensability honors key EJ and ecological prin- ciples by seeing all communities (more-than-human and human) as interconnected, interdependent, but also sovereign and requiring the solidarity of others. Indispens- ability should also not be confused with a Functionalist view of society and socio- ecological relations as it recognizes that social roles, positions, and behaviors among various populations can and do conflict and change over time, and that the character of inequality and state and market power in most societies is highly unjust and must be confronted. Functionalism, on the other hand, posits that whatever the character of inequality, social roles, and behaviors may be, it must be positive for society and there- fore is in no need of change (Parsons 1954 ). Indispensability argues against that logic because CEJ Studies is fundamentally focused on securing justice and sustainability in a highly unjust and unsustainable system. Thus indispensability demands dramatic change but does so from the perspective that all members of society and socioecologi- cal systems have something to contribute to that process and to our collective futures. Socially, politically, philosophically, and ecologically, what this means is that we are all linked in webs of social interdependence, so that what happens to one group affects, in some way, all others. As Dr. Martin Luther King, Jr. famously wrote in his landmark “Letter from Birmingham Jail” with regard to racism and the future of the United States: “Injustice anywhere is injustice everywhere. . . . In a real sense all life is inter-related. All men are caught in an inescapable network of mutuality, tied in a single garment of destiny. Whatever affects one directly, affects all indirectly. Never again can we afford to live with the narrow, provincial ‘outside agitator’ idea . . .” (King 1963 ). Thus the importance of CEJ studies here is to underscore that social systems predicated on the annihilation of Black life reveal a self-defeating error. In other words, the idea that Whiteness can only triumph and survive via the annihilation of Black life commits the classic ecological error of dualism or separation . Dualism is the idea that we see various categories of existence as separate and arranged in oppo- sitional hierarchies, such as culture/nature, man/woman, European/non-European, human/animal, White/Black, heterosexual/homosexual, etc., when in fact these cate- gories are constantly blurred, transgressed, and revealed to be socially constructed and highly fluid and malleable. So CEJ Studies facilitates an understanding that a vision of White supremacy premised on the destruction of people of color is as illogical and self-defeating as a vision of an economy and a nation-state premised on the destruc- tion of ecosystems. In a sense, this observation demonstrates a reality of social systems as ecosystems, and vice versa: that everything in the universe is hitched to everything at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X https://www.cambridge.org/core David N. Pellow 232 DU BOIS REVIEW: SOCIAL SCIENCE RESEARCH ON RACE 13:2, 2016 else, so that what affects one member or element affects all of them. The destruction of people of color harms White people and it harms the more-than-human world, and vice versa, so CEJ Studies affirms that Black lives, the lives of people of color, are indis- pensable . Going further, the idea of socioecological indispensability reflects the CEJ Studies perspective that the wellbeing of all people, species, and ecosystems is indispensible . This is both a socioecological reality and an affirmation of a politics of solidarity and coalition building that firmly states “All of us or none!” Black Lives Matter activists routinely speak to this issue as well. In 2015, BLM issued a “State of the Black Union” in which they wrote, “None of us are free until all of us are free” ( DeclarationProject.org 2015). This is a variation on a quote that has been attributed to the likes of the poet Emma Lazarus, the Reverend Dr. Martin Luther King, Jr., and many others. It is also articulated powerfully in the Barry Mann song “None of Us Are Free,” which includes the chorus, “None of us are free, none of us are free, if one of us is chained, none of us are free.” Expressing this view more than a century ago, African American historian Anna Julia Cooper told a group of Black clergymen in 1892, “Only the Black woman can say ‘when and where I enter, in the quiet, undisputed dignity of my womanhood, without violence and without suing or special patronage, then and there the whole . . . race enters with me’” (Bailey 2004 , p. 56). A year later, making this claim even stronger, at the 1893 World’s Congress of Representative Women, Cooper stated: Let woman’s claim be as broad in the concrete as the abstract. We take our stand on the solidarity of humanity, the oneness of life, and the unnaturalness and injus- tice of all special favoritism, whether of sex, race, country, or condition. If one link of the chain is broken, the chain is broken. A bridge is no stronger than its weakest part, and a cause is not worthier than its weakest element. Least of all can woman’s cause afford to decry the weak. We want, then, as toilers for the universal triumph of justice and human rights, to go to our homes from this Congress demanding an entrance not through a gateway for ourselves, our race, our sex, or our sect, but a grand highway for humanity (Cooper 1892 ). BLM co-founder Alicia Garza echoes and articulates this idea as follows: #BlackLivesMatter doesn’t mean your life isn’t important—it means that Black lives, which are seen as without value within White supremacy, are important to your liberation. Given the disproportionate impact state violence has on Black lives, we understand that when Black people in this country get free, the benefits will be wide reaching and transformative for society as a whole. When we are able to end hyper-criminalization and sexualization of Black people and end the poverty, control, and surveillance of Black people, every single person in this world has a better shot at getting and staying free. When Black people get free, everybody gets free . This is why we call on Black people and our allies to take up the call that Black lives matter. . . . Our collective futures depend on it (Garza 2014 , emphasis added). DISCUSSION AND CONCLUSION Critical Environmental Justice Studies seeks to expand the field of EJ Studies to move beyond its conceptual, theoretical, disciplinary, and methodological limitations. Since that path is still very much in formation, this paper is an effort to chart one course in that direction with greater specificity. Critical EJ Studies draws from numerous fields at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X https://www.cambridge.org/core Critical Environmental Justice Studies DU BOIS REVIEW: SOCIAL SCIENCE RESEARCH ON RACE 13:2, 2016 233 of scholarship in order to produce more robust accounts for why environmental injus- tices occur and persist, for how human and nonhuman forces shape and are shaped by them, and for what environmental justice might look like. That is, the promise of CEJ Studies lies in its capacity to more fully explain the sources and consequences of our socioecological crises and develop more generative analyses of how social change efforts within and across species may meet those challenges. Finally, CEJ Studies can aid scholars and advocates in thinking through a redefi- nition of the concept of environmental justice itself . Perhaps any discussion regarding the future of EJ Studies and the EJ movement might begin by connecting early EJ scholarship, which centers primarily around the intersection of social inequality and environmental harm, with the concept of ecological justice , which centers on the rela- tionship of human beings to the broader nonhuman world. By the term ecological justice, I mean to suggest a more respectful and egalitarian relationship of human beings to one another and to the greater more-than-human world. This model of analy- sis and politics begins with humans taking responsibility for practicing transforma- tive socioecological political work and extends to understanding inequalities within and across species and space to imagine and struggle for a more democratic multi- species world. Nonhuman species and ecosystems may not engage in politics the way humans tend to, but they can and do exert influence and power over the world (Bennett 2009 ): for example, consider the impacts of fossil fuels on the daily lives of human beings and on the political systems and economies of every nation on Earth. Ecological justice destabilizes the notion of the human as a biological category at the apex of a human/nature hierarchy and, instead, embraces it as a political cat- egory that engages with the broader ecological community. This model of politics also rejects the state as an arbiter of justice and inclusion. The state has managed, included, excluded, homogenized, and controlled humans and nonhuman natures for the benefit of a small elite. That should be reason enough to consider the merits of an anarchist or anti-authoritarian approach to socioecological change. Curiously, this concept of ecological justice closely mirrors and parallels the Principles of Envi- ronmental Justice—a sort of founding document of the U.S. EJ movement, suggest- ing that, in many ways, the EJ movement and EJ Studies have yet to catch up to the vision of the movement’s founding principles, which are largely aligned with a CEJ Studies perspective. In this paper, I applied a Critical Environmental Justice perspective to the phenomenon of the Black Lives Matter movement, demonstrating how attention to multiple categories of difference and inequality (including more-than-human species and the built environment); an emphasis on the role of scale as a way of understanding the violence of racism and the promise of resistance movements; a focus on linking the entrenched character of social inequalities with transformative, anti-authoritarian and anarchist perspectives; and an application of the concepts of racial and socioecological indispensability can produce an enriched account of that movement’s core concerns, its limitations, and its possibilities. Black Lives Matter challenges the scourge of state- sanctioned violence against diversely constituted communities of African descent, with a primary emphasis on police brutality and mass incarceration. I argue that if we think of environmental racism as an extension of those state-sanctioned practices—in other words a form of authoritarian control over bodies, space, and knowledge systems— then we can more effectively theorize it as a form of state violence, a framework that is absent from most EJ scholarship. Corresponding author : David N. Pellow, Environmental Studies Program, University of California Santa Barbara, 4312 Bren Hall, Santa Barbara, CA 93106-4160. E-mail: pellow@es.ucsb.edu at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X https://www.cambridge.org/core David N. Pellow 234 DU BOIS REVIEW: SOCIAL SCIENCE RESEARCH ON RACE 13:2, 2016 NOTES 1. After the November 2015 police killing of Jamar Clark, an unarmed African American male in Minneapolis, Minnesota, Black Lives Matter protesters demanded that the state prosecute the officers involved. The state declined to do so. 2. For exceptions, see, e.g., Liam Downey ( 2015 ) and Andrea Smith ( 2005 ). REFERENCES Adams , Carol J . ( 2010 ). The Sexual Politics of Meat: A Feminist-vegetarian Critical Theory . London : Bloomsbury Academic . Adamson , Joni ( 2011 ). Medicine Food: Critical Environmental Justice Studies, Native North American Literature, and the Movement for Food Sovereignty . Environmental Justice , 4 ( 4 ): 213 – 219 . Agyeman , Julian , Peter Cole , Randy Haluza-DeLay , and Pat O’Riley (Eds). ( 2010 ). Speaking for Ourselves: Environmental Justice in Canada . Seattle, WA : University of Washington Press . Ascione , Frank ( 1997 ). Battered Women’s Reports of Their Partners’ and Their Children’s Cruelty to Animals . Journal of Emotional Abuse , 1 ( 1 ): 119 – 133 . Bailey , Cathryn ( 2004 ). Anna Julia Cooper: ‘Dedicated in the Name of My Slave Mother to the Education of Colored Working People.’ Hypatia , 19 ( 2 ): 56 – 73 . Bell , Shannon Elizabeth ( 2013 ). Our Roots Run Deep as Ironweed: Appalachian Women and the Fight for Environmental Justice . Champaign, IL : University of Illinois Press . Bennett , Jane ( 2009 ). Vibrant Matter: A Political Ecology of Things . Durham, NC : Duke University Press . Bijan , Stephen ( 2015 ). Social Media Helps Black Lives Matter Fight the Power. Wired, November 2015 . < http://www.wired.com/2015/10/how-black-lives-matter-uses-social-media-to-fight- the-power/ > (accessed June 2, 2016). BlackLivesMatter.com ( 2016 ). All #BlackLivesMatter: This is Not a Moment, but a Movement. < http://www.blacklivesmatter.com/about > (accessed June 23, 2016). BlackLivesMatter.com ( 2015 ). DOJ: Protect Black Activists from White Vigilante Violence. < https://www.facebook.com/BlackLivesMatter/posts/513206922183891 > (accessed June 23, 2016). Brydum , Sunnivie ( 2015 ). Alicia Garza Taking Black Lives Matter into Another Dimension. The Advocate , December 9. < http://www.advocate.com/40-under-40/2015/12/09/alicia-garza- taking-black-lives-matter-another-dimension > (accessed June 2, 2016). Buckingham , Susan and Rakibe Kulcur ( 2010 ). Gendered Geographies of Environmental Justice . In Ryan Holifield , Michael Porter , and Gordon Walker (Eds.), Spaces of Environmental Justice , pp. 70 – 94 . New York : Wiley-Blackwell . Bullard , Robert D . ( 2000 ). Dumping in Dixie: Race, Class, and Environmental Quality . Boulder, CO : Westview Press . Cacho , Lisa ( 2012 ). Social Death: Racialized Rightlessness and the Criminalization of the Unprotected . New York : New York University Press . Change.org ( 2015 ). Terminate Officer Jennifer Lynne Silver. Online petition to Baltimore Mayor Stephanie Rawlings-Blake. April. < https://www.change.org/p/mayor-stephanie- rawlings-blake-commissioner-anthony-batts-captain-douglas-irwin-terminate-officer- jennifer-lynne-silver > (accessed June 23, 2016). Cole , Luke and Sheila Foster ( 2000 ). From the Ground Up: Environmental Racism and the Rise of the Environmental Justice Movement . New York : New York University Press . Collins , Patricia Hill ( 2008 ). Black Feminist Thought . New York : Routledge . Cooper , Ana Julia ( 1892 ). A Voice from the South . New York : Aldine Printing . Cullors , Patrisse ( 2015 ). Interview on Democracy Now! July 24. < http://www.democracynow. org/2015/7/24/part_2_blacklivesmatter_founders_on_immigration > (accessed June 2, 2016). Dahl , Robert ( 2005 ). Who Governs? Democracy and Power in an American City . New Haven, CT : Yale University Press . DeclarationProject.org ( 2015 ). State of the Black Union. January 22. < http://www.declara- tionproject.org/?p=1654 > (accessed June 23, 2016). Domhoff , G. William ( 2013 ). Who Rules America? The Triumph of the Corporate Rich . New York : McGraw-Hill Education Downey , Liam ( 2015 ). Inequality, Democracy and the Environment . New York : New York University Press . at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X https://www.cambridge.org/core Critical Environmental Justice Studies DU BOIS REVIEW: SOCIAL SCIENCE RESEARCH ON RACE 13:2, 2016 235 Ellison , Keith and Van Jones ( 2015 ). Pollution Isn’t Colorblind. The Guardian , July 24. < http://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2015/jul/23/black-lives-matter-air-pollution > (accessed June 2, 2016). Fantz , Ashley , George Howell , and Catherine Shoichet ( 2014 ). Gunshots, Tear Gas in Missouri Town Where Police Shot Teen. CNN.com , August 12. < http://www.cnn.com/2014/08/11/ us/missouri-teen-shooting/ > (accessed June 2, 2016). Friedersdorf , Conor ( 2015 ). The Brutality of Police Culture in Baltimore. The Atlantic , April 22. < http://www.theatlantic.com/politics/archive/2015/04/the-brutality-of-police-culture-in- baltimore/391158/ > (accessed June 2, 2016). Furst , Randy ( 2016 ). Protesters Demand Prosecution of Officers Involved in Jamar Clark Shooting. Minneapolis Star Tribune , February 12. < http://m.startribune.com/protesters- demand-prosecution-of-officers-involved-in-jamar-clark-shooting/368675951/ > (accessed June 22, 2016). Gaard , Greta ( 2004 ). Toward a Queer Ecofeminism . In Rachel Stein (Ed.), New Perspectives on Environmental Justice , pp. 21 – 44 . New Brunswick, NJ : Rutgers University Press . Garza , Alicia ( 2014 ). A Herstory of the #BlackLivesMatter Movement. The Feminist Wire , December 6. < http://www.thefeministwire.com/2014/10/blacklivesmatter-2/ > (accessed June 2, 2016). Garza , Alicia ( 2015 ). Interview on Democracy Now! July 24. < http://www.democracynow. org/2015/7/24/part_2_blacklivesmatter_founders_on_immigration > (accessed June 2, 2016). Gilmore , Ruth Wilson ( 2007 ). Golden Gulag: Prisons, Surplus, Crisis, and Opposition in Globalizing California . Berkeley, CA : University of California Press . Goldberg , David Theo ( 2002 ). The Racial State . Oxford, UK : Blackwell Publishers . Griswold , Alex ( 2015 ). CNN Guest: Black Men ‘Hunted Down Like Deer and Like Dogs.’ The Daily Caller , April 14. < http://dailycaller.com/2015/04/14/cnn-guest-black-men-in-america- hunted-down-like-deer-and-like-dogs-video/ > (accessed June 2, 2016). Harlan , Sharon , David N. Pellow , and J. Timmons Roberts , with Shannon Elizabeth Bell , William G. Holt , and Joane Nagel ( 2015 ). Climate Justice and Inequality . In Riley Dunlap and Robert J. Brulle (Eds.), Climate Change and Society: Sociological Perspectives , pp. 127 – 163 . Oxford, UK : Oxford University Press . Herod , Andrew ( 2011 ). Scale . London : Routledge . Holifield , Ryan , Michael Porter , and Gordon Walker ( 2010 ). Introduction—Spaces of Envi- ronmental Justice—Frameworks for Critical Engagement . In Ryan Holifield , Michael Porter , and Gordon Walker (Eds.), Spaces of Environmental Justice , pp. 1 – 22 . Oxford, UK : Wiley-Blackwell . Hong , Grace Kyungwon Hong ( 2006 ). Ruptures of American Capital: Women of Color Feminism and the Culture of Immigrant Labor . Minneapolis, MN : University of Minnesota Press . Kang , Jerry ( 2005 ). Trojan Horses of Race . Harvard Law Review , 118 : 1489 – 1593 . King , Martin Luther , Jr . ( 1963 ). Letter from Birmingham Jail. < https://www.africa.upenn. edu/Articles_Gen/Letter_Birmingham.html > (accessed August 5, 2016). Lombardi , Kristen , Talia Buford , and Ronnie Greene ( 2015 ). Environmental Justice, Denied. Center for Public Integrity. August 3. < https://www.publicintegrity.org/environment/ environmental-justice-denied > (accessed March 1, 2016). Márquez , John ( 2014 ). Black-Brown Solidarity . Austin, TX : University of Texas Press . Mills , Charles ( 2001 ). Black Trash . In Laura Westra and Bill E. Lawson (Eds.), Faces of Environ- mental Racism , pp. 73 – 93 . Lanham, MD : Rowman & Littlefield . Moore , Darnell and Patrisse Cullors ( 2014 ). 5 Ways to Never Forget Ferguson—And Deliver Real Justice for Michael Brown. The Guardian.com , September 4. < https://www.theguardian. com/commentisfree/2014/sep/04/never-forget-ferguson-justice-for-michael-brown > (accessed on June 22, 2016). Morris , Aldon ( 1984 ). Origins of the Civil Rights Movement . New York : Free Press . Nazaryan , Alexander ( 2014 ). The U.S. Department of Defense is one of the World’s Biggest Polluters. Newsweek , July 17. < http://www.newsweek.com/2014/07/25/us-department-defence- one-worlds-biggest-polluters-259456.html > (accessed March 1, 2016). Nibert , David and Michael W. Fox ( 2002 ). Animal Rights/Human Rights . Lanham, MD : Rowman and Littlefield . Nichols , Jason ( 2015 ). Black Baltimore Residents Aren’t ‘Animals.’ We Punish People for Killing ‘Animals.’ The Guardian , April 28. http://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2015/ apr/28/black-baltimore-residents-arent-animals-we-punish-people-for-killing-animals > (accessed June 2, 2016). Parsons , Talcott ( 1954 ). Essays in Sociological Theory . New York : The Free Press . at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X https://www.cambridge.org/core David N. Pellow 236 DU BOIS REVIEW: SOCIAL SCIENCE RESEARCH ON RACE 13:2, 2016 Pellow , David N . ( 2007 ). Resisting Global Toxics . Cambridge, MA : The MIT Press . Pellow , David N. and Robert J. Brulle (Eds.) ( 2005 ). Power, Justice, and the Environment . Cambridge, MA : The MIT Press . Pulido , Laura ( 1996 ). A Critical Review of the Methodology of Environmental Racism Research . Antipode , 28 ( 2 ): 142 – 159 . Ringquist , E. J . ( 2005 ). Assessing Evidence of Environmental Inequities . Journal of Policy Analysis and Management , 24 ( 2 ): 223 – 247 . Roberts , J. Timmons and Bradley Parks ( 2006 ). A Climate of Injustice . Cambridge, MA : The MIT Press . Scott , James ( 2010 ). The Art of Not Being Governed . New Haven, CT : Yale University Press . Smith , Andrea ( 2005 ). Conquest: Sexual Violence and American Indian Genocide . Boston, MA : South End Press . Smith , Mick ( 2011 ). Against Ecological Sovereignty . Minneapolis, MN : University of Minnesota Press . Smits , David ( 1994 ). The Frontier Army and the Destruction of the Buffalo: 1865-1883 . The Western Historical Quarterly , 25 ( 3 ): 312 – 338 . Sze , Julie ( 2006 ). Boundaries and Border Wars: DES, Technology, and Environmental Justice . American Quarterly , 58 ( 3 ) 791 – 814 . Sze , Julie ( 2016 ). Scale . In Joni Adamson , William Gleason , and David N. Pellow (Eds.), Keywords for Environmental Studies , pp. 178 – 180 . New York : New York University Press . Tometi , Opal ( 2015 ). Interview on Democracy Now! July 24. < http://www.democracynow. org/2015/7/24/part_2_blacklivesmatter_founders_on_immigration > (accessed June 2, 2016). Vargas , Joao H. Costa ( 2010 ). Never Meant to Survive: Genocide and Utopias in Black Diaspora Communities . Lanham, MD : Rowman & Littlefield . Walker , Gordon ( 2010 ). Beyond Distribution and Proximity: Exploring the Multiple Spatiali- ties of Environmental Justice . In Ryan Holifield , Michael Porter , and Gordon Walker (Eds.), Spaces of Environmental Justice , pp. 24 – 46 . Oxford, UK : Wiley-Blackwell . Williams , David R. and Chiquita Collins ( 1995 ). U.S. Socioeconomic and Racial Differences in Health: Patterns and Explanations . Annual Review of Sociology , 21 : 349 –86. at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Carnegie Mellon University, on 06 Apr 2021 at 02:20:26, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of use, available https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms https://doi.org/10.1017/S1742058X1600014X https://www.cambridge.org/core work_hmtgbexb3ndqtdfoktbo5ct5j4 ---- wp-p1m-39.ebi.ac.uk Params is empty 404 sys_1000 exception wp-p1m-39.ebi.ac.uk no 221738797 Params is empty 221738797 exception Params is empty 2021/04/06-03:20:37 if (typeof jQuery === "undefined") document.write('[script type="text/javascript" src="/corehtml/pmc/jig/1.14.8/js/jig.min.js"][/script]'.replace(/\[/g,String.fromCharCode(60)).replace(/\]/g,String.fromCharCode(62))); // // // window.name="mainwindow"; .pmc-wm {background:transparent repeat-y top left;background-image:url(/corehtml/pmc/pmcgifs/wm-nobrand.png);background-size: auto, contain} .print-view{display:block} Page not available Reason: The web page address (URL) that you used may be incorrect. Message ID: 221738797 (wp-p1m-39.ebi.ac.uk) Time: 2021/04/06 03:20:37 If you need further help, please send an email to PMC. Include the information from the box above in your message. Otherwise, click on one of the following links to continue using PMC: Search the complete PMC archive. Browse the contents of a specific journal in PMC. Find a specific article by its citation (journal, date, volume, first page, author or article title). http://europepmc.org/abstract/MED/ work_hp6aiugsubd6zm37dmbbmyyz74 ---- 23 ­Pomirenje Po­nov­no­us­po­sta­vlja­nje­prav­de­u­Sr­bi­ji­–­­ Po­mi­re­nje­i­re­sto­ra­tiv­na­prav­da­­ u­postkon­flikt­nom­kon­tek­stu Step han par Men ti er* Mar ta Va li ñaS el Mar We i te kaMp De ba ta o to me ka ko se ba vi ti pro šlo šću u Sr bi ji je i da lje pri sut na. Me ha ni zmi prav de Me đu na rod nog kri vič nog tri bu na la za biv šu Ju go sla vi ju i do ma ćih su do va od i gra li su va žnu ulo gu u kri vič nom go nje nju po či ni la ca zlo či na. O dru gim pri stu pi ma tran zi ci- o noj prav di i da lje se ras pra vlja. Sve u sve mu, is ku stva biv še Ju go sla vi je i Sr bi je sa „su o- ča va njem sa pro šlo šću” ili „tran zi ci o nom prav dom” su slič na is ku stvi ma dru gih ze ma lja, jer se od i gra va ju unu tar po li tič ke i eko nom ske eli te, i u okvi ru ci vil nog dru štva, ka ko u ze mlji o ko joj je reč, ta ko i na me đu na rod nom ni vou. Slič no, sta vo vi i oče ki va nja lo kal- nog sta nov ni štva u bi lo ko joj ze mlji se ret ko uzi ma ju u ob zir. U ovom ra du pred sta vlje ni su re zul ta ti is tra ži va nja na uzor ku ši re po pu la ci je ko je je spro veo naš is tra ži vač ki tim u Sr bi ji 2007. go di ne. Is tra ži va nje je vr še no pu tem an ke ti ra nja ši rom ze mlje u ve zi ne ko li ko pi ta nja ve za nih za post-kon flikt nu prav du, uklju ču ju ći tra ga nje za isti nom, od go vor nost, na kna du šte te žr tva ma i po mi re nje. Ključ ne re či: sta vo vi gra đa na, ljudska prava, re sto ra tiv na prav da, po mi re nje, Sr bi ja. TEMIDA Mart 2010, str. 23-41 ISSN: 1450-6637 DOI: 10.2298/TEM1001023P Izvorni naučni rad * Step han Par men ti er je pro fe sor so ci o lo gi je kri mi na la, pra va i ljud skih pra va na Uni ver zi te tu Le u ven, Belgija i na čel nik Ode lje nja za kri vič no pra vo i kri mi no lo gi ju. E-mail: step han.par- men ti er @law.ku le u ven.ac.be Mar ta Va li ñas je is tra ži va či ca i sa rad ni ca na Uni ver zi te tu Le u ven, Belgija gde za vr ša va svo ju dok tor sku di ser ta ci ju. E-mail: mar ta.va li nas @law.ku le u ven.be El mar We i te kamp je pro fe sor vik ti mo lo gi je i re sto ra tiv ne prav de na Uni ver zi te ti ma u Le u ve- nu, Belgija i Ti bin ge nu, Nemačka. E-mail: el mar.we i te kamp @u ni-tu e bin gen.de Step han Par men ti er, Mar ta Va li ñas, El mar We i te kamp 24 Uvod Še sna est go di na na kon po čet ka ras pa da Ju go sla vi je i su ko ba ko ji su opu- sto ši li ce lu re gi ju, ali naj vi še Hr vat sku, Bo snu i Her ce go vi nu, Sr bi ju i Ko so vo, sva ka od ze ma lja još uvek se tru di da pro na đe naj bo lji na čin da se po sta vi pre ma zlo či ni ma ko ji su se do go di li u pro šlo sti i nji ho vim po sle di ca ma i da ob no vi po ve re nje me đu svo jim gra đa ni ma. Ras pra va o to me ka ko se su o či ti s pro šlo šću u Sr bi ji je i da lje u to ku. Od 1993. go di ne, Me đu na rod ni kri vič ni sud1 za biv šu Ju go sla vi ju op tu žio je 161 oso bu, a od tog bro ja 120 li ca je pro šlo kroz pro ces su đe nja u 86 po stu pa ka (jun 2009) ve za nih za „me đu na rod na” kri vič na de la na pod ruč ju re gi o na. Ta ko đe, u sa moj ze mlji kre i ra ni su no vi me ha ni zmi kri vič nog pra vo su đa, kao što je Ve će za rat ne zlo či ne Okru žnog su da u Be o gra du. O dru gim pri stu pi ma tran zi ci o noj prav di kao što su Ko mi si ja za isti nu ili pro gra mi za na kna du šte te i da lje se ras pra vlja. De ba ta o „me đu na rod nim” zlo či ni ma iz pro šlo sti ta ko i da lje ima ve li ki zna čaj za lju de, or ga ni za ci je i in sti tu ci je u Sr bi ji. U ovom kon- tek stu „me đu na rod na” kri vič na de la kao re la tiv no no vi kon cept ne mo gu se po i sto ve ći va ti sa sta ri jim kon cep tom „dr žav nih” kri vič nih de la (Fri e drichs, 1998; Ka u zla rich, Mul lins i Mat thews, 2003): sa jed ne stra ne, „dr žav na” kri vič na de la pred sta vlja ju ši ru ka te go ri ju od „me đu na rod nih”, jer ona uklju ču ju i po na- ša nja ko ja se tra di ci o nal no ne sma tra ju na sil nim, kao što su de la iz da je, špi ju- na že i ko rup ci je; sa dru ge stra ne, „dr žav na” kri vič na de la su i uža od „me đu na- rod nih”, jer njih či ne oso be ili in sti tu ci je ko ji ma je po ve re na dr žav na vlast, dok „me đu na rod na” kri vič na de la mo gu bi ti uči nje na od stra ne ne dr žav nih ak te ra, kao što su ge ril ske gru pe ili in di vi due. Cen tral no pi ta nje ovog do pri no sa je ka ko raz u me ti po nov no us po sta vlja nje prav de za „me đu na rod na” kri vič na de la, po či nje na u Sr bi ji, uglav nom iz po li tič kih mo ti va. Sve u sve mu, is ku stva biv še Ju go sla vi je i Sr bi je sa „su o ča va njem sa pro šlo- šću” ili „tran zi ci o nom prav dom” su slič na is ku stvi ma dru gih ze ma lja, jer se od i- gra va ju unu tar po li tič ke i eko nom ske eli te, i u okvi ru ci vil nog dru štva, ka ko u ze mlji o ko joj je reč, ta ko i na me đu na rod nom ni vou. Slič no, sta vo vi i oče ki va- nja lo kal nog sta nov ni štva u bi lo ko joj ze mlji se ret ko uzi ma ju u ob zir. Ka da bi se to ura di lo, obez be dio bi se do dat ni iz vor in for ma ci ja o stra te gi ja ma i me ha- ni zmi ma za su o ča va nje sa zlo či ni ma iz pro šlo sti i za re kon struk ci ju bu duć- no sti. Iako su is tra ži va nja na uzor ku ši re po pu la ci je iz u ze tak, isti na je da smo 1 Vi di sajt: www.icty.org Temida 25 po sled njih go di na sve do ci br zog ra sta em pi rij skih is tra ži va nja spro ve de nih u post-kon flikt nim si tu a ci ja ma, a po ne kad i u to ku tra ja nja su ko ba (In ter na ti o nal Cen ter for Tran si ti o nal Ju sti ce, 2004, 2006, 2007). U ovom ra du pred sta vi će mo, po pr vi put, iz ve štaj o re zul ta ti ma is tra ži va nja na uzor ku ši re po pu la ci je ko je je naš is tra ži vač ki tim2 u Sr bi ji 2007. go di ne spro- veo pu tem an ke ti ra nja ši rom ze mlje u ve zi ne ko li ko pi ta nja ve za nih za post- kon flikt nu prav du. Mi će mo se sa mo fo ku si ra ti na je dan ta kav pro blem ov de – na po mi re nje iz me đu po je di na ca i iz me đu sek to ra u dru štvu. Glav ni ci lje vi na šeg do pri no sa su dvo ja ki: sa jed ne stra ne, že li mo po ka za ti vred nost em pi rij- skog is tra ži va nja na uzor ku lo kal nog sta nov ni štva o post-kon flikt noj prav di, a sa dru ge stra ne, na me ra nam je da is tak ne mo ove na la ze za ši ri te o rij ski okvir re sto ra tiv ne prav de kao pa ra dig me za po gled na zlo či ne iz pro šlo sti. Šta lju di u Sr bi ji mi sle o zlo či ni ma po či nje nim to kom ra ta i o stra te gi ja ma i me ha ni zmi ma za su o ča va nje sa stra ho ta ma iz pro šlo sti? To su dva glav na pi ta nja na osno vu ko jih smo is pla ni ra li i spro ve li kvan ti ta tiv no an ket no is tra- ži va nje na uzor ku srp ske po pu la ci je 2007. go di ne. Is tra ži va nje je bi lo deo ši reg is tra ži vač kog pro jek ta „Ma sov na vik ti mi za ci ja i re sto ra tiv na prav da“ u po tra zi za po zi ci jom re sto ra tiv ne prav de u in te gra tiv nom pri stu pu ma sov noj vik ti- mi za ci ji u post-kon flikt nim si tu a ci ja ma. Stu di je u Bo sni i Her ce go vi ni i Sr bi ji, oba vio je In sti tut za kri mi no lo gi ju na Ka to lič kom Uni ver zi te tu u Le u ve nu (Bel- gi ja) iz me đu 2004. i 2008. go di ne. Cilj ovog pro jek ta bio je da se is tra ži šta to mo že bi ti ulo ga i ka ko se mo gu pri me ni ti prin ci pi re sto ra tiv ne prav de u pro- ce su re ša va nja post-kon flikt nih si tu a ci ja ko je uklju ču ju ma sov nu vik ti mi za ci ju, uzi ma ju ći Sr bi ju i Bo snu i Her ce go vi nu kao dve stu di je slu ča ja i spro vo de ći dva vr lo slič na is tra ži va nja u obe ze mlje. Dok je fo kus is tra ži va nja bio na re sto- ra tiv noj prav di, tre ba lo bi po me nu ti da su sa me an ke te bi le usme re ne na još mno ga pi ta nja u obe post-kon flikt ne si tu a ci je. 2 Is tra ži vač ki tim či ni li su Step han Par men ti er i El mar We i te kamp (pro mo te ri) i Mar ta Va li ñas (is tra ži va či ca). Auto ri že le da se za hva le Ka to lič kom Uni ver zi te tu u Le u ve nu na fi nan sij skoj po dr šci za pro je kat, Fla man skom ake dem skom cen tru i Kra ljev skoj aka de mi ji za na u ku i umet nost u Bri se lu za stva ra nje sa vr še nih aka dem skih uslo va za do vr ša va nje ra da, pro fe so- ru Jo ha nu Go et hals-u i pro fe sor ki Ve sni Ni ko lić-Ri sta no vić iz Vik ti mo lo škog dru štva Sr bi je na kon struk tiv nim ko men ta ri ma na ra nu ver zi ju em pi rij skog de la is tra ži va nja. Is tra ži vač kom ti mu je Vik ti mo lo ško dru štvo Sr bi je pru ži lo ve li ku po moć. Ovaj rad je do pu nje na ver zi ja po gla vlja ko je će bi ti ob ja vlje no u knji zi: Par men ti er, S., Va li ñas, M., We i te kamp, E. (iz la zi u 2010) How to re sto re ju sti ce in Ser bia? A clo ser lo ok at pe o ple’s opi ni ons abo ut re con ci li a tion. In D. Rot he & C. Mul lins (eds.) Cri mes of Sta te: Cur rent Per spec ti ves. Pi sca ta way, NJ: Rut gers Uni ver sity Press. Step han Par men ti er, Mar ta Va li ñas, El mar We i te kamp 26 Cilj is tra ži va nja bio je da se sa zna ne što vi še o sta vo vi ma i mi šlje nji ma3 po je di na ca o pro ce su su o ča va nja sa pro šlo šću (ili tran zi ci o ne prav de) u Sr bi ji, sa po seb nim na gla skom na „mo guć no sti“ i po ten ci jal re sto ra tiv nog pri stu pa ta kvom pro ce su. Za ana li zu ovih sta vo va i mi šlje nja ko ri sti li smo he u ri stič ki TA RR mo del (Par men ti er, 2003; Par men ti er i We i te kamp, 2007). Ovaj mo del se sa sto ji od če ti ri gra div na blo ka ko ji od go va ra ju ključ nim pi ta nji ma u pro ce su su o ča va nja no vog re ži ma sa pro šlo šću, a to su: po tra ga za isti nom o pro šlo- sti (T), ka ko bi se osi gu ra la od go vor nost po či ni te lja (A) i ne ki ob lik re pa ra ci je za žr tve (R), ali i ka ko bi se pro mo vi sa lo po mi re nje iz me đu biv ših ne pri ja te- lja (R). Ovaj mo del pru ža ko ri stan okvir za ana li zu raz li či tih od no sa iz me đu dva ili vi še gra div nih blo ko va, omo gu ća va da se is tra že od re đe ne in sti tu ci je i me ha ni zmi su o ča va nja sa pro šlo šću u od no su na sva ko od ovih pi ta nja, a i su ge ri še da re zul tat pri stu pa tran zi ci o noj prav di pro iz i la zi iz me đu dej stva ova če ti ri gra div na blo ka (We i te kamp, Par men ti er, Van spa u wen, Va li ñas i Ge rits, 2006). An ke ti ra nje je spro ve de no ta ko da uklju či pi ta nja ve za na za sva ko od ova če ti ri ključ na pi ta nja. Me­tod Me tod is tra ži va nja ko ri šćen u ovoj stu di ji bi la je an ke ta spro ve de na kroz pi sa ne upit ni ke di stri bu i ra ne po ce loj Sr bi ji. Me to do lo gi ja se sa sto ja la od če ti ri osnov na ko ra ka (Va li ñas, Par men ti er i We i te kamp, 2008): 1) Kon struk ci ja in stru men ta za pri ku plja nje po da ta ka: u pi ta nju je od štam- pa ni upit nik sa ukup no 43 pi ta nja, od ko jih ne ka ima ju od go vo re ko ji is klju ču ju jed ni dru ge, ne ka ima ju vi še mo gu ćih od go vo ra, a ne ka od is pi- ta ni ka tra že da ozna če ste pen sla ga nja sa al ter na tiv nim od go vo ri ma na po sta vlje no pi ta nje. Sva ova pi ta nja bi la su za tvo re na ili po lu za tvo re na, sa jed nim iz u zet kom – po sled njim pi ta njem „Šta po mi re nje zna či za Vas?“ ko je je is pi ta ni ci ma omo gu ća va lo da iz ra ze svo je mi šlje nje na vr lo otvo- ren i ne de ter mi ni san na čin. Upit nik su kon stru i sa li čla no vi is tra ži vač kog ti ma u pe ri o du iz me đu fe bru a ra i ma ja 2006. go di ne, na osno vu sle de ćih 3 Stav je men tal na po zi ci ja u od no su na ne ku či nje ni cu ili sta nje. On od ra ža va ten den ci ju da se objek ti i do ga đa ji kla si fi ku ju i da se na njih re a gu je sa od re đe nom do sled no šću. Sta vo vi se ne mo gu di rekt no po sma tra ti, već se iz vla če iz objek tiv nih i eva lu i ra nih od go vo ra oso be. Mi šlje nja pred sta vlja ju ide je i mi sli ne ke oso be o ne če mu. To su pro ce ne, su do vi o ne če mu ili eva lu a ci je ne če ga. De fi ni ci je su pre u ze te iz Encyclo pa e dia Bri tan ni ca. Temida 27 iz vo ra: dva is tra ži va nja sa slič nim ci lje vi ma, pre ci zni je kom pa ra tiv na stu di ja spro ve de na na Maks Plank In sti tu tu za ino stra no i me đu na rod no kri vič no pra vo o vik ti mi za ci ji u ra tu (Ki za, Rat hge ber i Roh ne, 2006), kao i is tra ži va- nje UNDP-a u Bo sni i Her ce go vi ni (UNDP, 2005); po da ci ko je je is tra ži va či ca pri ku pi la to kom pret hod nih is tra ži va nja na te re nu u Sr bi ji uglav nom kroz po lu struk tu ri sa ne in ter vjue sa ključ nim ak te ri ma u pro ce su su o ča va nja sa pro šlo šću; po da ci pri ku plje ni na ra di o ni ci ko ju je or ga ni zi vao is tra ži vač ki tim u Du brov ni ku (Hr vat ska) u ma ju 2005. go di ne i na se mi na ru odr ža nom u Sa ra je vu (Bo sna i Her ce go vi na) u ok to bru 2006. go di ne, a oba su se ti ca la pro ce sa su o ča va nja sa pro šlo šću u re gi o nu. Upit nik je naj pre ko ri šćen u slič nom is tra ži va nju u Bo sni i Her ce go vi ni 2006. go di ne, a ka sni je je pri la- go đen spe ci fič noj si tu a ci ji u Sr bi ji. 2) Od re đi va nje od go va ra ju će me to de uzor ko va nja: s ob zi rom na po te ško će u ko ri šće nju po u zda nih po da ta ka iz po pi sa sta nov ni štva4 u Sr bi ji ni je bi lo mo gu će da se for mi ra pra vi re pre zen ta tiv ni uzo rak, pa je ume sto nje ga oda bran kvot ni uzo rak5. Ovo je pod ra zu me va lo de lje nje cilj ne po pu la ci je (gra đa ne i sta nov ni ke Sr bi je) u pod gru pe na osno vu tri kri te ri ju ma ko ji su nam bi li od zna ča ja: ge o graf ska di stri bu ci ja (ši rom dr ža ve, sa iz u zet kom Ko so va i Me to hi je), uz rast (usme re nost na ve li ku gru pu sta ro sti iz me đu 26 i 64 go di ne, ma nju gru pu iz me đu 18 i 25 go di na, kao i još jed nu ma nju gru pu sta ro sti pre ko 65 go di na) i pol (ujed na če ne gru pe mu ška ra ca i že na) i utvr đi va nje pro por ci je uzor ka u sva koj od ka te go ri ja. Za raz li ku od slič nog is tra ži va nja spro ve de nog u Bo sni i Her ce go vi ni, u Sr bi ji re li gi ja i et nič ka pri- pad nost ni su bi li raz dvo je ni kri te ri ju mi za kvot no uzor ko va nje, ali od is pi- ta ni ka je ste za tra že no da na ve du svo ju re li gij sku i et nič ku pri pad nost. 3) Pri ku plja nje po da ta ka kroz di stri bu ci ju upit ni ka: upit ni ci su po de lje ni u ju nu 2007. go di ne na 16 raz li či tih lo ka ci ja u Sr bi ji od stra ne pri pad ni ka 19 ne vla di nih or ga ni za ci ja ko je pri pa da ju Aso ci ja ci ji Za jed nič ka Ak ci ja za Isti nu i Po mi re nje6. Sva ka od ovih ne vla di nih or ga ni za ci ja ra di na pi ta nji ma 4 Ka da ka rak te ri sti ke po pu la ci je ni su u pot pu no sti ili do volj no po zna te, ni je mo gu će na pra vi ti re pre zen ta tiv ni uzo rak. Ta da uzo r ko va nje za sno va no na ve ro vat no ći i oda bir slu čaj nog uzor- ka ni su uvek ade kvat ni. 5 Raz li ka iz me đu kvot nog uzor ka (me to de uzor ko va nja ko ja ni je za sno va na na ve ro vat no ći) i stra ti fi ko va nog slu čaj nog uzor ka se sa sto ji u to me što kod kvot nog uzor ko va nja ko na čan iz bor po je di nač nih is pi ta ni ka za vi si od is tra ži va ča od no sno ni je slu ča jan (Bryman, 2008). 6 Pri stup ne vla di nim or ga ni za ci ja ma i is pi ta ni ci ma obez be đen je kroz bli sku sa rad nju sa Vi ki- mo lo škim dru štvom Sr bi je i ovom pri li kom se za hva lju je mo pro fe sor ki Ve sni Ni ko lić-Ri sta no- vić i Da ni je li Bje lić na po mo ći. Step han Par men ti er, Mar ta Va li ñas, El mar We i te kamp 28 po ve za nim sa pred me tom na šeg is tra ži va nja i ima raz li či te cilj ne po pu- la ci je (iz be gli ce, žr tve tor tu re, rat ni ve te ra ni, itd.). Or ga ni za ci ja ma su da ti sli čan broj upit ni ka (oko 50) i ja sne in struk ci je ve za ne za kri te ri ju me se lek- ci je is pi ta ni ka. Ka ko bi se osi gu ra la kom pa ti bil nost sa ra ni je pri ku plje nim po da ci ma u Bo sni i Her ce go vi ni, oso be ko je su de li le upit ni ke za mo lje ne su da deo upit ni ka da ju čla no vi ma svo jih or ga ni za ci ja, a deo osta lim gra- đa ni ma, uz po što va nje ano nim no sti svih is pi ta ni ka. Od ukup nog bro ja od 1200 upit ni ka, vra će no je i po pu nje no 922 od no sno 85% - vi sok pro ce nat ti pi čan za me to de pri god nog uzor ko va nja (Bryman, 2008). 4) Ana li za pri ku plje nih po da ta ka: kre i ra na je ma ska u SPSS pro gra mu i svi po da ci su une ti od stra ne me to do lo ga iz Sr bi je, ko ji je ta ko đe spro veo i ne ko li ko ni voa ana li ze, uklju ču ju ći i uni va ri jant ne i bi va ri jant ne ana li ze, ko re la ci je i re gre si o nu ana li zu. Svi po da ci pre zen to va ni u na red nom de lu tek sta re zul tat su ovog če tvo- ro ste pe nog pro ce sa pri ku plja nja i ana li ze po da ta ka. In­stru­ment Po što smo bi li sve sni uti ca ja rat nih is ku sta va po je di na ca na nji ho vo sa da- šnje mi šlje nje i sta vo ve pre ma te mi post-kon flikt ne prav de, po ku ša li smo da raz u me mo ka kav je bio tip i ste pen vik ti mi za ci je ko je su na ši is pi ta ni ci pre ži- ve li. Pr vi deo upit ni ka je za to bio po sve ćen pi ta nji ma ko ja su bi la ve za na za ob li ke di rekt ne (npr. fi zič ke po vre de is pi ta ni ka) i in di rekt ne vik ti mi za ci je (npr. gu bi tak čla na po ro di ce). Šta vi še, is pi ta ni ci su upi ta ni o to me ka ko su opa ža li svo ju pat nju kroz tri ob li ka: fi zič ki, ma te ri jal ni i psi ho lo ški i u dva vre men ska pe ri o da – pre i po sle ra ta. Od go vo ri su nam omo gu ći li da za klju či mo da je u na šem uzor ku naj vi še is pi ta ni ka pa ti lo emo tiv no to kom i na kon ra ta, ne što ma nje njih je pre tr pe lo ma te ri jal nu šte tu, a naj ma nje je bi lo onih sa po vre- da ma fi zič ke pri ro de. Ovi re zul ta ti su pot pu no sa gla sni sa re zul ta ti ma is tra ži- va nja spro ve de nog u Bo sni i Her ce go vi ni 2006. go di ne. Va žno je pri me ti ti da su is pi ta ni ci u is tra ži va nju u Sr bi ji pri ja vi li vik ti mi za ci ju ve za nu za tri glav na na sil na kon flik ta, rat u Hr vat skoj 1991-1995 (36%), NA TO bom bar do va nje 1999. go di ne (24%) i rat u Bo sni i Her ce go vi ni (20.8%). Ne ki is pi ta ni ci su pri ja vi li vik- ti mi za ci ju u ra tu na Ko so vu i Me to hi ji po čev od 1998. go di ne (15%), a ma li broj njih i u kon flik tu u Slo ve ni ji 1991. go di ne (4.2%). Dru gi deo upit ni ka sa dr žao je raz li či ta pi ta nja sme šte na pod če ti ri raz li či ta na slo va: tra ga nje za isti nom, Temida 29 omo gu ća va nje pri zna nja od go vor no sti, is pla ta od šte te i pro mo ci ja po mi re nja. U ovom ra du mi se ogra ni ča va mo na pri kaz ne kih aspe ka ta ve za nih za te mu po mi re nja u Sr bi ji. Pre ne go što pre đe mo na naj i stak nu ti je na la ze, va žno je na gla si ti da su sva pi ta nja po sta vlje nja svim is pi ta ni ci ma u is tra ži va nju, a ne sa mo oni ma ko ji bi mo gli da se oka rak te ri šu kao „žr tve“ u prav nom ili so ci o lo škom smi slu. Raz- log to me je taj što je u na sil nim kon flik ti ma (kao što je bio onaj u Ju go sla vi ji) prak tič no ne mo gu će na pra vi ti ta ko ja snu raz li ku iz me đu onih ko ji su sa mo po či ni o ci i onih ko ji su sa mo žr tve, po što po je din ci mo gu po ne kad pre u ze ti raz li či te ulo ge, čak ih i za me ni ti u raz li či tim fa za ma kon flik ta (Fri day, Hart man, Lord i Exum, 2007). Za po tre be ovog is tra ži va nja pre fe ri ra li smo da pi ta mo sve is pi ta ni ke u Sr bi ji ka kvu šte tu ve ru ju da su pre ži ve li za vre me i po sle ra ta i na taj na čin oti šli smo da lje od spe ci fič nog an ke ti ra nja žr ta va pro ši ru ju ći ga u is pi ti va nje ši re po pu la ci je. Re­zul­ta­ti Šta­gra­đa­ni­Sr­bi­je­mi­sle­o­po­mi­re­nju? Po mi re nje je bi lo ve o ma kon tro ver zan ter min i kon cept u biv šoj Ju go sla vi ji od za vr šet ka na sil nih kon fli ka ta. Za mno ge ono je pred sta vlja lo pret nju pre u- zi ma nju od go vor no sti za po či nje na kri vič na de la i iz tog raz lo ga ide ja po mi re- nja se su sre la sa sna žnim ot po rom, ka ko od po je di na ca, ta ko i od or ga ni za ci ja (do ma ćih i me đu na rod nih). U naj bo ljem slu ča ju ne ki su po dr ža li mi ni ma li stič ki pri stup po mi re nju. Jed no od za pa ža nja iz pret hod nog is tra ži va nja na te re nu je bi lo da je u dis kur su su o ča va nja sa pro šlo šću „po ve re nje“ mno go bo lje pri hva- će no od „po mi re nja“. Dok je po mi re nje iz gle da pod ra zu me va lo ne ki ob lik ne ka- žnja va nja ili pri hva ta nja da su dve stra ne ušle u kon flikt na isti na čin i sa istim ste pe nom od go vor no sti, po nov na iz grad nja po ve re nja pod ra zu me va la je da bi tre ba lo po pra vi ti pre ki nu te so ci jal ne od no se. Po mi re nje se mo že od i gra va ti na vi še ni voa – od in di vi du al nog, in ter per so nal nog, pre ko ni voa za jed ni ce, pa sve do na ci o nal nog ni voa, a u slu ča ju biv še Ju go sla vi je čak i na re gi o nal nom ni vou. U na šem is tra ži va nju po mi re nje je ana li zi ra no iz per spek ti ve od o zdo – na go re (bot tom-up), ali i iz per spek ti ve od o zgo – na do le (top-down). Shod no to me, is pi- ti va ni su i in di vi du al ni po gle di na vi še in ter per so nal ne pro ce se po mi re nja, kao i fak to ri na ma kro ni vou ko ji su olak ša va li ili ko či li pro ces po mi re nja u biv šoj Ju go- Step han Par men ti er, Mar ta Va li ñas, El mar We i te kamp 30 sla vi ji. Is tra ži va nje ve za no za po mi re nje u Sr bi ji ni je jed no sta van za da tak. U stva ri, u ve ći ni slu ča je va oni ko ji su se me đu sob no bo ri li u to ku ra ta ne ži ve vi še u is toj ze mlji (u ovom slu ča ju Sr bi ji) da nas. Ume sto to ga, mno gi od onih iz Sr bi je ko ji su ak tiv no uče stvo va li u ra tu bo ri li su se pro tiv onih ko ji su ži ve li, a i da lje ži ve iz van gra ni ca Sr bi je. Slič no, mno gi od onih ko ji su po sta li žr tve iz van gra ni ca Sr bi je, da nas ži ve u Sr bi ji. Iz ovih raz lo ga (sta vlja ju ći na tre nu tak na stra nu mno ge po sto- je će dru štve ne ten zi je iz me đu raz li či tih dru štve nih gru pa) mo že se re ći da u Sr bi ji ne po sto je ja sne ka te go ri je žr ta va i po či ni la ca u kla sič nom smi slu (npr. ka da jed na oso ba uči ni ne što pro tiv ne ke dru ge). Kao re zul tat te či nje ni ce, mi smo for mu li sa li na ša pi ta nja o po mi re nju u ter mi ni ma od no sa iz me đu raz li či tih et nič kih gru pa ko je su bi le uklju če ne u kon flik te u biv šoj Ju go sla vi ji (Ta be la 1). U ve zi mo guć no- sti po mi re nja iz me đu raz li či tih et nič kih gru pa, od no si iz me đu Sr ba i Slo ve na ca se is ti ču po naj ve ćem bro ju (76.9%) po zi tiv nih od go vo ra u smi slu da je mo gu će po mi re nje iz me đu njih. Od no si iz me đu Sr ba i Al ba na ca sa Ko so va i Me to hi je se ta ko đe is ti ču, ali kao oni za ko je po sto ji ma nja na da za po mi re nje, po seb no u slu ča ju ko sov skih Sr ba i ko sov skih Al ba na ca. Ve ći na is pi ta ni ka sma tra da u ovim od no si ma po mi re nje ni je mo gu će: 39.6% za od nos Sr ba i ko sov skih Al ba na ca i 40.7% za od nos ko sov skih Sr ba i ko sov skih Al ba na ca. U od no si ma iz me đu Sr ba i Hr va ta, Sr ba i Bo šnja ka i Hr va ta i Bo šnja ka, pre ko po lo vi na is pi ta ni ka ve ru je da je po mi re nje mo gu će (54%, 54.8% i 54.2%), ne što ma nje njih ni je si gur no (23.6%, 25.8% i 32.5%), a još ma nje ve ru je da ni je mo gu će (22.4%, 19.4% i 13.2%). Ta be la 1. Da li mi sli te da je mo gu će da se pri pad ni ci sle de ćih et nič kih gru pa po mi re? Et nič ke gru pe Da Ne Ne znam Sr bi i Slo ven ci 76.9% 7.9% 15.3% Sr bi i Hr va ti 54% 22.4% 23.6% Sr bi i Bo šnja ci 54.8% 19.4% 25.8% Hr va ti i Bo šnja ci 54.2% 13.2% 32.5% Sr bi iz Sr bi je i Al ban ci sa KiM 32.8% 39.6% 27.6% Sr bi sa KiM i Al ban ci sa KiM 31.9% 40.7% 27.3% Ne do sta ju ći po da ci: a) 4.8%, b) 5.7%; c) 5.7%, d) 6.6%, e) 6.8%, f) 6.7%. Ka da se pi ta nje o po mi re nju for mu li še u ter mi ni ma ko ji se vi še od no se na lič no is ku stvo, od no sno ka da se is pi ta ni ci pi ta ju da li bi mo gli da se po mi re sa oso ba ma ko je su od go vor ne za nji ho vu vik ti mi za ci ju, pro ce nat onih ko ji od go- va ra ju sa „ne“ se po ve ća va. Ovo pi ta nje je for mu li sa no u op štim ter mi ni ma, od no sno bez spe ci fi ko va nja et nič ke gru pe žr tve i/ili po či ni o ca (Ta be la 2). U sva- Temida 31 kom slu ča ju, mo gu će je vi de ti da je pro ce nat is pi ta ni ka ko ji su od go vo ri li „ne“ na ovo pi ta nje (40.3%) ve ći ne go u svim slu ča je vi ma gde su is pi ta ni ci od go va ra li o mo guć no sti po mi re nja iz me đu raz li či tih et nič kih gru pa, osim u slu ča ju od no sa ko sov skih Sr ba i ko sov skih Al ba na ca (gde je ta ko đe 40.7% is pi ta ni ka pro ce ni lo da je za njih ne mo gu će da se po mi re). Na rav no ove pro cen te bi tre ba lo in ter pre- ti ra ti sa opre zom, jer je sa mo tre ći na is pi ta ni ka od go vo ri la na ovo pi ta nje. Ta be la 2. Da li mi sli te da je mo gu će da se po mi ri te sa oso ba ma ko je su Vam na u di le? Od go vor Fre kven ci ja Pro ce nat Da 86 23.6% Ne 147 40.3% Ne znam 132 36.2% Ne do sta ju ći po da ci: 7.4% Ako po gle da mo et nič ku dis tri bu ci ju ovih od go vo ra (Ta be la 3), mo že mo vi de ti da su svi al ban ski is pi ta ni ci re kli da ne bi mo gli da se po mi re, kao i ve ći na bo šnjač kih is pi ta ni ka (59.5%) iako je ve li ki broj njih od go vo rio sa „ne znam”. Me đu Hr va ti ma, ve ći na je re kla da ne zna (60%), dok su srp ski is pi ta- ni ci po no vo naj vi še po de lje ni (re la tiv na ve ći na od 37.5% je re kla „ne“, 34.9% je re klo da ne zna i 27.6% je od go vo ri lo „da”). U po re đe nju sa dru gim gru pa ma (pro por ci o nal no) Sr bi su ti ko ji su naj vi še sprem ni da se po mi re. Me đu tim, zbog ogra ni če nog bro ja oso ba ko je su od go vo ri le na ovo pi ta nje, ove re zul- ta te je neo p hod no in ter pre ti ra ti sa opre zom. Ta be la 3. Da li mi sli te da je mo gu će da se po mi ri te sa oso ba ma ko je su Vam na u di le? Od go vor Al ban ci Bo šnja ci Hr va ti Ma đa ri Ro mi Sr bi Ne de kla ri sa ni Osta li Da 0% 9.5% 10% 20% 33.3% 27.6% 0% 16.7% Ne 100% 59.5% 30% 20% 33.3% 37.5% 45.5% 33.3% Ne znam 0% 31% 60% 60% 33.3% 34.9% 54.5% 50% Ne do sta ju ći po da ci: 7.4% Ta ko đe, re for mu li sa li smo pi ta nje o po mi re nju u ter mi ni ma po ve re nja iz me đu raz li či tih gru pa i is pi ta ni ci su upi ta ni da oce ne ko li ko su od re đe ni fak- to ri po mo gli ili od mo gli pro ces po nov ne iz grad nje po ve re nja iz me đu ovih gru pa u biv šoj Ju go sla vi ji. Iz re zul ta ta pro is ti če za klju čak da su glav ne pre- pre ke („uop šte ni su po mo gli” i „ni su po mo gli”) u pro ce su po nov ne iz grad nje po mi re nja po is pi ta ni ci ma sle de će: Step han Par men ti er, Mar ta Va li ñas, El mar We i te kamp 32 Tra u ma ko ju po je din ci još uvek tr pe zbog ra ta (52%)• Sta vo vi i stra te gi je po li ti ča ra (50.6%)• Kri vič no go nje nje pred • Me đu na rod nim su dom za rat ne zlo či ne po či nje ne na pod ruč ju biv še Ju go sla vi je (49.5%) Ško le (46.1%)• Kri vič no go nje nje pred do ma ćim su do vi ma (44.4%).• Sa dru ge stra ne fak to ri za ko je is pi ta ni ci sma tra ju da su po mo gli („po mo- gli su pu no” i „po mo gli su“) ovom pro ce su su: Po zi tiv na se ća nja lju di o vre me nu pre ra ta (66.3%)• Vre me ko je je pro šlo od za vr šet ka ra ta (60%)• Pri zna nje tu đe pat nje (53.9%)• Ulo ga ne vla di nih or ga ni za ci ja (53.1%).• Ra zna za ni mlji va za pa ža nja se mo gu iz vu ći iz ovih pro ce na ta. Naj pre, fak tor oko ko ga su is pi ta ni ci po ka za li naj ve ću po de lje nost u mi šlje nju bi la je ulo ga me di ja: 42.9% is pi ta ni ka je re klo da su me di ji bi li pre pre ka u pro ce su po nov ne iz grad nje po ve re nja, dok je 41.2% re klo da mi sle da su me di ji po mo- gli taj pro ces. Slič no, pri su stvo i ulo ga me đu na rod ne za jed ni ce ta ko đe su pod- sta kle raz li či te re ak ci je: 40.8% is pi ta ni ka sma tra da je me đu na rod na za jed ni ca pre pre ka, a 39.3% da je po mo gla pro ce su. Bit no je pri me ti ti i da je tra u ma pre- po zna ta kao naj ve ća pre pre ka u ovom pro ce su, što na gla ša va va žnost emo- ci o nal ne tra u me kao i či nje ni cu da je ona če sto za po sta vlje na u jav nom dis- kur su i u od lu ka ma vla de i do na to ra. Još jed no va žno za pa ža nje je to da su kri vič na go nje nja vi đe na kao pre pre ka pro ce su po nov ne iz grad nje po ve re nja, po go to vo ona ko ja se de ša va ju pred Me đu na rod nim su dom za rat ne zlo či ne po či nje ne na pod ruč ju biv še Ju go sla vi je, ali i ona pred do ma ćim su do vi ma. Ko nač no, ovi re zul ta ti nam uka zu ju da dva fak to ra za ko je is pi ta ni ci sma tra ju da naj vi še po ma žu pro ces po nov nog us po sta vlja nja po ve re nja ni su po ve za na ni sa ka kvim po li tič kim od lu ka ma ili me ha ni zmi ma, već da ima ju vi še spon- ta nu i psi ho lo šku pri ro du. Ovo na me će pi ta nje da li se ustva ri po nov na iz grad- nja po ve re nja mo že in du ko va ti spo lja ili da li ta či nje ni ca zna či da su do sad usvo je ne po li tič ke od lu ke i me ha ni zmi vi đe ni kao ne u spe šni u tom smi slu7. 7 Za de talj ni je upo zna va nje sa pro ce som po mi re nja vi de ti: Blo om fi eld, Bar nes i Huyse, 2003; Daly i Sar kin, 2007. Temida 33 Po me nu ti re zul ta ti nam ja sno go vo re, da iako su za ni mlji vi, po ne kad ih je te ško in ter pre ti ra ti bez ne kih kon tek stu al nih in for ma ci ja. Ka ko bi se išlo da lje u raz u me va nju po mi re nja u ovom is tra ži va nju, sma tra li smo da je neo p hod no da se is pi ta ni ci pi ta ju šta za njih pred sta vlja po mi re nje. Od lu či li smo se za me tod otvo re nog pi ta nja ka ko ne bi smo ogra ni či li ili in du ko va li od go vo re, a to je pri stup ko ji je po ve ćao vred nost po da ta ka do bi je nih po sta vlja njem ovog pi ta nja. Ipak, ka ko bi smo kvan ti ta tiv no ob ra di li ove po dat ke u sta ti stič kim ter- mi ni ma i u od no su na dru ga pi ta nja u upit ni ku, mo ra li smo da kom bi nu je mo kva li ta tiv ne i kvan ti ta tiv ne me to de ana li ze. Ovo je zah te va lo po ve ći ste pen in ter pre ta ci je od stra ne is tra ži vač kog ti ma. Sva kom od go vo ru je pri do da ta ši fra – je din stve na (jed na od ba zič nih ši fa ra) ili kom bi no va na (od dve ili vi še je din stve nih). Li sta je din stve nih ši fa ra je na pra vlje na na osno vu pre li mi nar nog pre gle da od go vo ra, pri če mu su u ob zir uze ti i spe ci fič ni ci lje vi is tra ži va nja kao i zna nje pri ku plje no od stra ne is tra ži vač kog ti ma u pret hod nom te ren skom is tra ži va nju. Na osno vu to ga, raz li či te re či i iz ra zi su do bi li od re đe no zna če nje i gru pi sa ni su u raz li či te ka te go ri je ili ši fre. Su bjek tiv nost ko ja je ne mi nov no ugra đe na u ovaj pro ces je ba lan si ra na kroz uklju či va nje asi sten ta is tra ži va ča ko ji je re ko di rao sve od go vo re. Ovi po da ci su on da une ti i ana li zi ra ni kvan- ti ta tiv no u SPSS-u. Ko nač ni re zul tat ovog po du hva ta su po da ci o to me ka ko is pi ta ni ci opi su ju po mi re nje: mir na ko eg zi sten ci ja (21.9%), opra šta nje (12%), po što va nje / to le ran ci ja (11.9%), pri hva ta nje od go vor no sti (8.8%) i isti na (6.2%). Sle de: kri vič no go nje nje (3.4%), za bo ra vlja nje (3.3%), po ve re nje (3.1%) i se ća nje (2.9%). Ovi pro cen ti se od no se i na one slu ča je ve ka da su ovi kon cep ti po me- nu ti po je di nač no ili u kom bi na ci ji sa dru gim kon cep ti ma. Va­žnost­re­sto­ra­tiv­ne­prav­de­za­„me­đu­na­rod­na”­kri­vič­na­de­la­iz­pro­šlo­sti Cilj pro jek ta ko ji je omo gu ćio okvir za ovo is tra ži va nje bio je i da se is tra že mo guć no sti za pri me nu prin ci pa re sto ra tiv ne prav de u pro ces su o ča va nja sa pro šlo šću u Sr bi ji. Is pi ti va nje ši re po pu la ci je je tre ba lo da do pri ne se i bo ljem raz u me va nju to ga ka ko is pi ta ni ci vi de glav na pi ta nja post-kon flikt ne prav de, sa po seb nim na gla skom na po ten ci jal re sto ra tiv nog pri stu pa u ta kvim pro ce- si ma. Dru gim re či ma, ka da je bi lo po treb no su o či ti se sa tra ga njem za isti nom, pri hva ta njem od go vor no sti, re pa ra ci ja ma i po mi re njem, ovo is tra ži va nje je is pi ta lo va žnost ko ju is pi ta ni ci pri da ju ele men ti ma re sto ra tiv nog pri stu pa, kroz pi ta nja ve za na za ne ke osnov ne ele men te te o ri ja i prak si re sto ra tiv ne prav de. Je dan od ovih ele me na ta je i su sret. Pre ma de fi ni ci ja ma re sto ra tiv ne prav de Step han Par men ti er, Mar ta Va li ñas, El mar We i te kamp 34 usme re nim na pro ces, su prot sta vlje ne stra ne u kon flik tu bi tre ba lo da ko lek- tiv no re še taj isti kon flikt (Mar shall, 1996). Ova for mu la ci ja mo že se de kon stru i- sa ti u sle de će prin ci pe: in klu zi ju, ak tiv nu par ti ci pa ci ju i su sret (Va li ñas i Van spa- u wen, 2009). Su sre tu je u ma nje ili vi še po sre do va noj for mi, da va na cen tral na va žnost u pro ce si ma re sto ra tiv ne prav de. Is ku stva su sre ta iz me đu onih ko ji su od go vor ni za na si lje i onih ko ji su bi li žr tve bi lo je u vi še post-kon flikt nih pod- ruč ja kao što su Ju žno a frič ka Re pu bli ka, Is toč ni Ti mor i Se ver na Ir ska. U ovom is tra ži va nju is pi ta ni ci su upi ta ni da li bi vo le li da se sret nu sa oni ma ko ji su ih po vre di li (tzv. di rekt nim po či ni o ci ma). Re la tiv na ve ći na (42.4%) is pi ta ni ka je da la od go vor „ne”, 35.1% je re klo „da”, a 22.6% je od go vo ri la da ne zna (Ta be la 4). Ono što po no vo pri me ću je mo ov de je, kao i kod mno gih dru gih kon tr o ve r zni jih ili ose tlji vi jih pi ta nja u upit ni ku, da, iako po sto ji ap so- lut na ve ći na ko ja ni je sprem na za ta kav su sret, ona je da le ko od pre o vla da va- ju će ve ći ne. Bi lo bi va žno ov de na po me nu ti da od svih is pi ta ni ka, njih 79.9% ni je lič no po zna va lo lju de ko ji su ih po vre di li, a da je sa mo 20.1% njih (sva ka pe ta oso ba) po zna va lo po či ni o ce. Ka da po no vo po gle da mo et nič ku di stri bu- ci ju od go vo ra vi di mo da su Sr bi oni kod ko jih je naj vi še po de la u mi šlje nji ma: 40% njih ka že da ne bi vo le lo da sret ne po či ni o ca, 31% da bi vo le lo, a 29% da ne zna ju šta da od go vo re na to pi ta nje. Hr va ti su ta ko đe do sta po de lje ni oko ovog pi ta nja, dok su Bo šnja ci si gur ni ji da ne že le ta kve su sre te (45.5% Hr va ta je re klo „ne” na su prot 51.8% Bo šnja ka). Me đu oni ma ko ji su re kli da bi vo le li da sret nu po či ni o ce, ve ći na je mu ška ra ca (55.3%), ali, na rav no, broj is pi ta ni ka ko ji su od go vo ri li na ovo pi ta nje ni je ve li ki. Ta be la 4. Da li bi ste vo le li da se sret ne te sa oso ba ma ko je su Vam na u di le? Od go vor Fre kven ci ja Pro ce nat Da 129 35.1% Ne 156 42.4% Ne znam 83 22.6% Ne do sta ju ći po da ci: 6.6% Od is pi ta ni ka ko ji su od go vo ri li da bi vo le li da sret nu one ko ji su ih po vre- di li na ne ki na čin, za tra že no je da ob ja sne raz lo ge za tu že lju. Na ve šće mo od go vo re is pi ta ni ka od onih naj va žni jih pa do onih ma nje va žnih: da bi ih pi tao/-la za što su ura di li to što su ura di li• da bi imao/-la pri li ku da im ka žem ka ko sam pa tio/-la• da bih vi deo/-la da li se ka ju zbog to ga što su ura di li• Temida 35 da bih vi deo/-la da li će se iz vi ni ti• da bih tra žio/-la od njih da po pra ve šte tu ko ju su mi na pra vi li• da bih ih pi tao/-la o mo jim ne sta lim ro đa ci ma i pri ja te lji ma.• Dva glav na mo ti va is pi ta ni ka (za su sret sa oni ma ko ji su im na ne li bol) su pri- lič no če sti i u dru gim slu ča je vi ma su sre ta žr ta va i po či ni la ca. Po ku šaj da se na đe smi sao u pat nji ko ja je ne ko me iza zva na i pri li ka da se ne što o njoj ka že ka ko bi po či ni lac bio sve stan po sle di ca svo jih de la, če sta su od li ka ova kvih su sre ta, a pred sta vlja ju i deo pro ce sa is ce lje nja. Dru ga dva raz lo ga – da se vi di da li se po či ni o ci ka ju ili iz vi nja va ju, ta ko đe su pred vi dlji vi mo ti vi za ta kve su sre te. Ipak, ta kvi mo ti vi mo gu pro u zro ko va ti ve li ke po te ško će, jer na go ve šta va ju da mo žda po sto je ne re a li stič ka oče ki va nja na stra ni žr ta va ko ja mo gu do ve sti do fru stra ci je i raz bi ja nja ilu zi ja to kom i po sle su sre ta8. Iz ne na đu ju će je vi de ti da is pi ta ni ci ni su pri da li ve ći zna čaj pi ta nju re pa ra ci je. Ovo iz gle da su ge ri še da is pi ta ni ci, ko ji su bi li vik ti mi zi ra ni, pre sve ga tra že psi ho lo šku i emo ci o nal nu „na dok na du šte te” u su sre tu sa po či ni o cem. Jed no od mo gu ćih ob ja šnje nja je da je po sle rat na sce na u Sr bi ji i u biv šoj Ju go sla vi ji u ve li koj me ri oka rak te ri sa na kao sce na sa ne pre kid- nim po ri ca njem i ne do stat kom pri zna va nja ono ga što se de si lo u pro šlo sti. Ipak, tre ba lo bi pri me ti ti da je shva ta nje zna če nja re či „re pa ra ci ja” kod ovog pi ta nja vi še aso ci ra no sa ma te ri jal nom na dok na dom šte te, upr kos ne dav nom raz vo ju i pro ši ri va nju kon cep ta ka ko bi se uklju či le i do dat ne ka te go ri je9. Is pi ta ni ci ko ji su od go vo ri li da ni su že le li da se sret nu sa lju di ma ko ji su im na u di li, ta ko đe su upi ta ni za raz lo ge ta kvog sta va. Raz lo zi ko je su na vo di li, po re đa ni po fre kven ci ji ja vlja nja od naj če šćeg do naj ma nje če stog su: ne že lim da vi dim tu oso bu po no vo i že lim da za bo ra vim ono što se de si lo• ako bih ga sreo/-la po no vo bih pa tio/-la• 8 Kom bi na ci ja po ka zi va nja ka ja nja i iz vi nje nja za de la iz pro šlo sti od stra ne po či ni o ca bi naj ve- ro vat ni je pred sta vlja la naj bo lju for mu pri zna nja žr tva ma i no si la bi naj ve ći re pa ra tiv ni po ten- ci jal, ali ta kav ide al ni is hod ne mo že se ga ran to va ti žr tva ma. Ne ki eks per ti u obla sti re sto ra tiv- ne prav de upo zo ri li su da ka ja nje i iz vi nje nja ne bi tre ba lo da bu du oče ki va ni is ho di su sre ta, ali da bi ih tre ba lo sa ra do šću pri hva ti ti kao spo re dan re zul tat, kao i da bi bi lo sa svim do volj no i ako bi po či ni lac pri stao da pru ži od šte tu žr tvi bez po ka zi va nja ka ja nja ili iz vi nja va nja. Ta kvu ide ju je za stu pao i ko mi tet za am ne sti ju Ju žno a frič ke Ko mi si je za isti nu i po mi re nje pred ko jim je pred u slov do bi ja nja am ne sti je bio iz no še nje či nje ni ca u pot pu no sti, a ka ja nje, ža lje nje i iz vi- nje nja ni su bi li neo p hod na (Wal gra ve, 1994; Par men ti er, 2001; Par men ti er i We i te kamp, 2005). 9 Iz ve štaj Van Bo u ven/Bas si o u ni do veo je do osnov nih prin ci pa i pre po ru ka ve za nih za re pa- ra ci ju u ko ji ma je re pa ra ci ja vi đe na kao ši ri kon cept ko ji uklju ču je re sti tu ci ju, kom pen za ci- ju, re ha bi li ta ci ju, sa tis fak ci ju i ga ran ci ju da se de lo ne će po no vi ti (Uni ted Na ti ons Ge ne ral As sembly, 2006; Shel ton, 2005; Rom bo uts i Par men ti er, 2009). Step han Par men ti er, Mar ta Va li ñas, El mar We i te kamp 36 ne znam za što• mr zim tu oso bu• pla šim se te oso be.• Iz gle da da je za is pi ta ni ke iz be ga va nje kon tak ta ili su sre ta sa po či ni o- cem po ve za no sa iz be ga va njem po nov ne pat nje (uglav nom zbog pri se ća- nja pro šlo sti) ili u naj ma nju ru ku zbog ose ća nja ne pri jat no sti. Ova ose ća nja su po ve za na sa psi ho lo škim pro ce si ma (ili me ha ni zmi ma od bra ne) kroz ko je žr tve pro la ze ka da se su o ča va ju sa eks trem nim bo lom ili pat njom i za to se na njih po ne kad ne mo že la ko uti ca ti ni ti iza zva ti pro me na u nji ma spo lja. Ovo je gru pa lju di ko ja se ne ose ća sprem nom da do ži vi ta kav su sret. Za ni mlji vo je, me đu tim, da dva naj ja ča ose ća nja ov de pred sta vlje na kao mo gu ći raz lo zi da se od bi je ta kav su sret – strah i mr žnja, uop šte ni su če sto na vo đe ni od go vo ri. Opra šta nje je če sta i kon tro verz na te ma u de ba ti o po mi re nju, ali i u li te- ra tu ri ve za noj za re sto ra tiv nu prav du. Mno gi su tvr di li da je za po mi re nje neo p hod no opro sti ti i isto vre me no od ba ci ti že lju za osve tom. Iako po mi re- nje kao kon cept per se ni je ta ko če sto po mi njan u te o ri ja ma o re sto ra tiv noj prav di, pro ces di ja lo ga i raz me ne u ko ji stra ne ula ze je po sma tran kao po ten- ci jal no do bar za raz vi ja nje em pa ti je me đu stra na ma i ko nač no za opra šta nje od stra ne žr ta va. Opra šta nje je, me đu tim, po sta lo ve o ma kon tra verz no pi ta- nje u dru štvi ma u tran zi ci ji, ko ja se su o ča va ju sa te škim po vre da ma ljud skih pra va. Če sto je bi lo po ve zi va no sa za ma ski ra nim te žnja ma za ne ka žnja va njem. Ali čak i ka da pro ces pri hva ta nja od go vor no sti pra ti opra šta nje, kao što je to bio slu čaj u Ju žnoj Afri ci, mno gi su ga kri ti ko va li kao sta vlja nje no vog te re ta na one ko ji su već bi li ozbilj no vik ti mi zi ra ni. I po red kon tr o ve r ze, opra šta nje na sta vlja da bu de glav na te ma u ze mlja ma ko je se bo re da se su o če sa stra- šnim zlo či ni ma i da na sta ve da lje. Is pi ta ni ci ko ji su re kli da bi bi li sprem ni da se su sret nu sa po či ni o ci ma upi ta ni su i da li bi mo gli da opro ste po či ni o ci ma ako bi u to ku tog su sre ta po či ni lac is ka zao iskre no ka ja nje i pri znao od go vor nost za nji ho vu pat nju. Pod jed nak broj is pi ta ni ka je re kao da bi mo gao da opro sti, kao i da ne zna (39.4%), dok je 21.3% re klo da ne bi mo glo da opro sti. Temida 37 Ta be la 5. Ka da bi ste sre li oso bu ko ja Vam je na u di la i ka da bi ona pri zna la šta Vam je ura di la i po ka za la da se iskre no ka je zbog to ga, da li bi ste ta da mo gli da joj opro sti te? Od go vor Fre kven ci ja Pro ce nat Da 73 39.4% Ne 78 21.3% Ne znam 116 39.4% Ne do sta ju ći po da ci: 1.6% Do sta vi sok pro ce nat od ma log bro ja is pi ta ni ka ko ji je uop šte od go vo rio na ovo pi ta nje, ni je znao šta da od go vo ri, zbog ose tlji ve pri ro de sa mog pi ta- nja ko je ote ža va da se raz mi šlja u hi po te tič kim ter mi ni ma. Sa dru ge stra ne, mo ra mo se za pi ta ti da li ovo pi ta nje pod ra zu me va ono što bi se mo glo na zva ti uslov nim opro šta jem (od no sno opro šta jem sa mo uz pret hod no is pu nje nje od re đe nih uslo va, u ovom slu ča ju pri zna va njem od go vor no sti i pat nje žr ta va i is ka zi va njem ka ja nja). Uzi ma ju ći u ob zir či nje ni cu da zna mo da su ovi uslo vi te ško ostva ri vi i da su is pi ta ni ci u pret hod nim pi ta nji ma da li ve li ki zna čaj iz vi- nje nji ma, ka ja nju i pri zna va nju kri vi ce, mo že se za klju či ti da i da lje po sto ji ve li ki pro ce nat onih ko ji ne zna ju da li bi mo gli i onih ko ji zna ju da ni su sprem ni da opro ste. Ka da se po gle da ju od go vo ri na ovo pi ta nje u od no su na et nič ko po re- klo is pi ta ni ka, Sr bi su u ve ćem pro cen tu bi li sprem ni da opro ste (41.7%), dok su Al ban ci naj ma nje sprem ni da opro ste (50% je re klo da ne bi mo glo, a 50% da ne zna da li bi mo glo). Hr va ti su ve o ma po de lje ni u svo jim mi šlje nji ma, jer po lo vi na njih ni je zna la šta da od go vo ri, a dru ga po lo vi na je bi la rav no prav no po de lje na iz me đu od go vo ra „da” i „ne”. Bo šnja ci su ta ko đe bi li po de lje ni, iako je re la tiv na ve ći na njih re kla da ne bi mo gla da opro sti (41.7%). Za­klju­čak Cen tral no pi ta nje ovog ra da bi lo je: ka ko raz u me ti po nov no us po sta vlja- nje prav de za „me đu na rod na” kri vič na de la u Sr bi ji. Ka ko bi da li od go vor na ovo pi ta nje, pred sta vi li smo ne ke re zul ta te is tra ži va nja na ši roj po pu la ci ji spro- ve de nog od stra ne na šeg is tra ži vač kog ti ma u Sr bi ji 2007. go di ne, sa po seb- nim fo ku som na ne ke aspek te ve za ne za po mi re nje iz me đu po je di na ca i iz me đu sek to ra dru štva. Kroz ovo is tra ži va nje po ku ša li smo da do pri ne se mo bo ljem raz u me va nju mi šlje nja i sta vo va po je di na ca ko ji ži ve u Sr bi ji o to me ka ko bi sa pro šlo šću mo glo Step han Par men ti er, Mar ta Va li ñas, El mar We i te kamp 38 i tre ba lo da se su o či i po seb no da li i ka ko re sto ra tiv ni pri stup mo že bi ti deo ta kvog pro ce sa. Po sta lo je ja sno da su pi ta nja opra šta nja, po ve re nja i po mi re nja me đu naj kon tra verz ni jim te ma ma ko je je upit nik po krio. U tom smi slu ve o ma je va žno da se pro u či ras po de la od go vo ra na pi ta nja, ali i da se uzme u ob zir gru pa is pi ta ni ka či ja su mi šlje nja bi la po me ša na ili ne si gur na, od no sno oni ko ji su se od lu či li za od go vor „ne znam”. Još jed no bit no za pa ža nje je da se mi šlje nja o ovim te ma ma, po seb no o po mi re nju, me nja ju ka da se sta ve na ap strakt ni ji ili lič- ni ji ni vo. Šta vi še, iako po mi re nje tre nut no ima ne ga tiv nu ko no ta ci ju u Sr bi ji, zbog tri vi ja li za ci je tog poj ma u jav nom dis kur su, ono je ve ro vat no vi đe no kao re al ni je od po nov nog us po sta vlja nja po ve re nja. A u pro ce su po nov ne iz grad nje po ve re- nja po sto ji kon sen zus o ne ga tiv noj ulo zi po li ti ča ra i tra u me. Sprem nost i uslo vi za opra šta nje su da lje ana li zi ra ni u kon tek stu su sre ta iz me đu su ko blje nih stra na ko je se i da lje na la ze na li ni ji po de le stvo re ne ra tom. Su sret je bio cen tral ni ele ment pro gra ma re sto ra tiv ne prav de i ta ko đe je bio in te gri san u od re đe ne me ha ni zme ko ji su bli ski re sto ra tiv noj fi lo zo fi ji u kon tek stu tran zi ci je po sle ve li kih su ko ba. Mo ra po sta ti ja sno da ta kvi su sre ti pod ra zu me va ju od re đen ste pen pri pre me i uče šća svih stra na, što se ne mo že uvek obez be di ti, kao što su za mi šlja li is pi ta ni ci u ovom is tra ži va nju. Mo žda je za to vi še is pi ta ni ka od go vo ri lo da ni je sprem no da se su sret ne sa oni ma ko ji su ih vik ti mi zi ra li, ali tre ba lo bi uze ti u ob zir i či nje ni cu da ve ći na is pi ta ni ka ni je lič no po zna va la te oso be. Za pa ža nja ove vr ste po ja vi la su se i u dru gim pro ce si ma su o ča va nja sa pro šlo šću gde je opra šta nje po sta lo deo na ci o nal ne stra te gi je i re to ri ke su o ča va nja sa pro šlo šću, po ne kad iza zi va ju ći oštre re ak ci je od stra ne onih ko ji su sma tra li da opra šta nje mo že bi ti sa mo in di vi du a lan i pri- va tan pro ces, za vi stan od mno go broj nih okol no sti i uslo va, a u sva kom slu ča ju ve o ma te žak i dug pro ces. Ovo is tra ži va nje su ge ri še da su i po sle vi še od 16 go di na po sle po čet ka ras pa da Ju go sla vi je mno ga ključ na pi ta nja u su o ča va nju sa pro šlo šću i da lje ve o ma pri sut na u de ba ti o to me ka ko kre nu ti na pred. Ova ras pra va bi mo gla da po sta ne bo lja, ako bi se u pi ta nje do ve le od re đe ne pret po stav ke o to me ka ko pri zna va nje i pre u zi ma nje od go vor no sti mo že da se za ga ran tu je i ka ko da se po stig ne po mi re nje. Ko ji pri stup pri me ni ti u pro ce su su o ča va nja sa pro- šlo šću - da li pri mar no re tri bu tiv ni ili re sto ra tiv ni, pi ta nje je ko je je neo p hod no po sta vi ti u tre nut nom kon tek stu u Sr bi ji. Iz tog raz lo ga bi lo je ja ko va žno pi ta ti re pre zen ta tiv ni deo po pu la ci je o nji ho vim mi šlje nji ma i sta vo vi ma. Is tra ži va- nje u Sr bi ji po ka za lo je da mno gi za ni mlji vi re zul ta ti mo gu pro iz i ći iz ta kvog po du hva ta, kao i hi po te ze za bu du ća is pi ti va nja. Na da mo se da smo ta ko Temida 39 do pri ne li glav nim ci lje vi ma ovog ra da – da se de mon stri ra vred nost em pi rij- skih is tra ži va nja post-kon flikt ne prav de na lo kal nom sta nov ni štvu i da se ovi na la zi po sta ve kao pa ra dig ma za po gled na „me đu na rod na” kri vič na de la iz pro šlo sti u ši rem te o rij skom okvi ru re sto ra tiv ne prav de. Li­te­ra­tu­ra Blo om fi eld, D., Bar nes, T., Huyse, L. (eds.) (2003) Re con ci li a tion Af ter Vi o lent Con flict – A Hand bo ok. Stoc kholm: In ter na ti o nal Idea. Bryman, A. (2008) So cial Re se arch Met hods. Ox ford: Ox fo rd Uni ver sity Press. Daly, E., Sar kin, J. (eds.) (2007) Re con ci li a tion in Di vi ded So ci e ti es – Fin ding Com mon Gro und. Phi la delp hia: Uni ver sity of Pennsylva nia Press. Fri e drichs, D. (ed.) (1998) Sta te Cri me: Vo lu mes 1 & 2. Al der shot: As hga te/Dart mo uth. In ter na ti o nal Cen ter for Tran si ti o nal Ju sti ce (2004) Ira qi Vo i ces: At ti tu des to wards Tran- si ti o nal Ju sti ce and So cial Re con struc tion. New York: Hu man Rights Cen tre, Uni ver sity of Ber ke ley Ca li for nia/ In ter na ti o nal Cen ter for Tran si ti o nal Ju sti ce. In ter na ti o nal Cen ter for Tran si ti o nal Ju sti ce (2006) Co lom bian Per cep ti ons and Opi ni- ons on Ju sti ce, Truth, Re pa ra ti ons, and Re con ci li a tion. New York: In ter na ti o nal Cen ter for Tran si ti o nal Ju sti ce In ter na ti o nal Cen ter for Tran si ti o nal Ju sti ce (2007) When the War Ends: A Po pu la tion Ba sed Sur vey of At ti tu des abo ut Pe a ce, Ju sti ce, and So cial Re con struc tion in Nort hern Ugan da. New York: Hu man Rights Cen tre, Uni ver sity of Ber ke ley Ca li for nia/ In ter na ti- o nal Cen ter for Tran si ti o nal Ju sti ce. Ka u zla rich, D., Mul lins, C., Mat thews, R. (2003) A com pli city con ti nu um of sta te cri me. Con tem po rary Ju sti ce Re vi ew, 6(3), str. 241-254. Ki za, E., Rat hge ber, C., Roh ne, H. (2006) Vic tims of war: an em pi ri cal study on war, vic- ti mi sa tion and vic tims’ at ti tu des to wa rds ad dres sing atro ci ti es. Ham burg: Ham bur ger Edi tion. Mar shall, T. (1996) The Evo lu tion of Re sto ra ti ve Ju sti ce in Bri tain. Euro pean Jo ur nal on Cri mi nal Po licy and Re se arch, 4(4), str. 21-43. Par men ti er, S. (2001) The So uth Afri can Truth and Re con ci li a tion Com mis sion. To wards Re sto ra ti ve Ju sti ce in the Fi eld of Hu man Rights, in Fat tah, Ez zat & Par men- ti er, S. (eds.), Vic tim Po li ci es and Cri mi nal Ju sti ce on the Road to Re sto ra ti ve Ju sti ce. Es says in Ho no ur of Tony Pe ters, 401-428, Le u ven, Le u ven Uni ver sity Press. Step han Par men ti er, Mar ta Va li ñas, El mar We i te kamp 40 Par men ti er, S. (2003) Glo bal Ju sti ce in the Af ter math of Mass Vi o len ce. The ro le of the In ter na ti o nal Cri mi nal Co urt in De a ling with Po li ti cal Cri mes. In ter na ti o nal An nals of Cri mi no logy, 41(1-2), str. 203-224. Par men ti er, S. and We i te kamp, E. (2005) The Truth and Re con ci li a tion Com mis sion in So uth Afri ca, in Na ta ra jan, M. (ed.), In tro duc tion to In ter na ti o nal Cri mi nal Ju sti ce, 151- 158, New York, McGraw-Hill. Par men ti er, S., We i te kamp, E. (2007) Po li ti cal Cri mes and Se ri o us Vi o la ti ons of Hu man Rights: To wards a Cri mi no logy of In ter na ti o nal Cri mes. In S. Par men ti er & E. We i te- kamp (eds.) Cri me and Hu man Rights – Se ri es in So ci o logy of Cri me, Law and De vi an ce, vol. 9. Am ster dam/Ox ford: El se vi er/JAI Press, str. 109-144. Rom bo uts, H., Par men ti er, S. (2009) The In ter na ti o nal Cri mi nal Co urt and its Trust Fund are Co ming of Age: To wards a Pro cess Ap pro ach for the Re pa ra tion of Vic tims. In ter na ti o nal Re vi ew of Vic ti mo logy, 16(2), str. 149-182. Shel ton, D. (2005) The Uni ted Na ti ons Prin ci ples and Gu i de li nes on Re pa ra ti ons: Con- text and Con tents. In K. De Feyter, S. Par men ti er, M. Bos suyt & P. Lem mens (eds.) Out of the As hes – Re pa ra tion for Vic tims of Gross and Syste ma tic Hu man Rights Vi o la ti ons. Ant werp/Ox ford: In ter sen tia, str. 11-33. UNDP (2005) Early War ning System Spe cial Edi tion – Ju sti ce and Truth in Bo snia and Her- ze go vi na: Pu blic Per cep ti ons. Sa ra je vo: UNDP. Uni ted Na ti ons Ge ne ral As sembly (2006) Ba sic Prin ci ples and Gu i de li nes on the Right to a Re medy and Re pa ra tion for Vic tims of Gross Vi o la ti ons of In ter na ti o nal Hu man Rights Law and Se ri o us Vi o la ti ons of In ter na ti o nal Hu ma ni ta rian Law: re so lu tion / adop ted by the Ge ne ral As sembly, 21.3.2006 – A/RES/60/147. Pre u ze to 15.3.2010. sa: http://www.un hcr.org/ref world/do cid/4721cb942.html Va li ñas, M., Par men ti er, S., We i te kamp, E. (2008) Sur vey ‘Re sto ring Ju sti ce in Ser bia’ – Pre li mi nary Re port. Le u ven: Fa culty of Law & Le u ven In sti tu te of Cri mi no logy. Va li ñas, M., Van spa u wen, K. (2009) The pro mi se of Re sto ra ti ve Ju sti ce in the se arch for truth af ter a vi o lent con flict - Ex pe ri en ces from So uth Afri ca and Bo snia-Her ze go- vi na. Con tem po rary Ju sti ce Re vi ew, 12(3), str. 269-287. Wal gra ve, L. (1994) Beyond Re ha bi li ta tion: In Se arch of a Con struc ti ve Al ter na ti ve in the Ju di cial Re spon se to Ju ve ni le Cri me, 2(2) Euro pean Jo ur nal on Cri mi nal Po licy and Re se arch (Spe cial Is sue on the Ju ve ni le Ju sti ce System) str. 57-75, 62-67. We i te kamp, E., Par men ti er, S., Van spa u wen, K., Va li ñas, M., Ge rits, R. (2006) How to deal with mass vic ti mi za tion and gross hu man rights vi o la ti ons. A re sto ra ti ve ju sti ce ap pro ach. In U. Ewald & K. Tur ko vić (eds.) Lar ge Sca le Vic ti mi sa tion as a Po ten tial So ur ce of Ter ro rist Ac ti vi ti es – Im por tan ce of Re ga i ning Se cu rity in Post-Con flict So ci e ti es. Am ster dam: IOS Press, str. 217-241. Temida 41 Step han par Men ti er Mar ta Va li ñaS el Mar We i te kaMp Re­sto­ring­ju­sti­ce­in­Ser­bia­–­Re­con­ci­li­a­tion­­ and­re­sto­ra­ti­ve­ju­sti­ce­in­a­post-war­con­text The de ba te on how to deal with the past in Ser bia is an on go ing one. Both the In ter na ti o nal Cri mi nal Tri bu nal for ex-Yugo sla via and na ti o nal cri mi nal ju sti ce mec ha- nisms ha ve played an im por tant ro le in pro se cu ting of fen ders. Ot her tran si ti o nal ju sti ce ap pro ac hes con ti nue to be di scus sed. All in all, the Yugo slav and the Ser bian ca ses are si mi lar to ot her de ba tes abo ut ‘de a ling with the past’ or ‘tran si ti o nal ju sti ce’, as they are ta king pla ce bet we en eli tes, po li ti cal, eco no mic, and wit hin ci vil so ci ety, both in the co un try con cer ned and at the in ter na ti o nal le vel. Li ke wi se the vi ews and ex pec ta- ti ons of the lo cal po pu la ti ons in any gi ven co un try are very ra rely ta ken in to ac co unt. In this pa per fin dings of a po pu la tion-ba sed re se arch car ried out by our re se arch te am in Ser bia in 2007 are pre sen ted. The re se arch was do ne by me ans of a qu an ti ta ti ve sur- vey ac ross the co un try on se ve ral is su es of post-con flict ju sti ce, in clu ding truth se e king, ac co un ta bi lity, re pa ra tion for vic tims and re con ci li a tion. Keywords: ci ti zen at ti tu des, hu man rights, re sto ra ti ve ju sti ce, re con ci li a tion, Serbia. Sa en gle skog je zi ka pre veo: Ni ko la M. Pe tro vić work_hpi4unf2pjerhdrkuplpeidapy ---- Editorial: No Economic Justice without Gender Justice Upfront Editorial: No Economic Justice without Gender Justice WENDY HARCOURT It seems incredible in these days of economic crisis that over 2,200 women (and some men) found the time and money to fly to Istanbul for a discussion on gender and economic justice at the AWID Forum 2012. Registrations closed a week before the event opened and the majority of the 800 organizations and individuals who answered the call for sessions and papers could not be accommodated. Like many who attended, I spent months preparing for the event.With AWID, I orga- nized in autumn a special meeting to plan this journal issue. I contributed to designing and participating in three of the sessions. And in the weeks in the run up to the event, I was continually promising my network of colleagues and friends that we would meet up in Istanbul to plot, to listen to each other’s sessions, or find a corner somewhere to catch up. Like many others, I came to Istanbul to learn, to find and renew friendships, to be energized and to plan for the future. AWID Forums are special, highly charged, inclusive and exciting. The secret of their success is that, in the end, they are not events but the converging of many processes. The making and attending of an AWID Forum is part of a complex networking process that brings together different generations of feminists in a space to engage, to share and create. The Development journal has been fortunate to publish now three special editions covering the outcome of the AWID Forum1 working with the ever more international and dynamic AWID team. This journal issue is packed with insights. Cindy Clark and Lydia Alp|¤ zar DuraŁ n give a sizzling overview in their introduction of the main issues of the Forum from the epicentre of the Forum arrangements. The other articles in the Upfront section present highlights from the plenaries and in-depth sessions. Articles based on stirring speeches reflect new forms of activism and urgency in today’s crisis hung world. From the defiant revolutionary poem by Marwa Sharafeldin, to the talk of a fierce new world by Gita Sen and Marilyn Waring’s crisp critique of economic power; from Rhadika Balakrishnan plea for popular education, and the warnings of the misuse of culture by Yakin Ertuº rk, we sense a new dynamism and activism as women confront eco- nomic and social inequalities. Jayati Ghosh completes the section when she argues it is time for feminists to enter into the discussion of alternatives more forcefully in order to define how economic institutions and policies can ensure a gender-just economy and society. Development, 2012, 55(3), (257–259) r 2012 Society for International Development 1011-6370/12 www.sidint.net/development/ Development (2012) 55(3), 257–259. doi:10.1057/dev.2012.49; published online 13 July 2012 The Thematic section pushes further into how this engagement might happen with a series of articles setting out the structural reasons for the economic injustices that are impeding women’s lives. Feminist economists, most of whom spoke at the AWID Forum, go to the core of economic processes in order to give a gender reading of financialization of our lives; the impact of neo- liberal economic policies on women’s employ- ment; social protection policies; taxes; balancing family life; funding for women’s rights, environ- ment, well-being and livelihoods. The Dialogue section details a vision of change by setting out feminist alternative visions to the mainstream economic development model. The three articles present: howAWID is engaged with many women’s rights networks exploring alterna- tives; what is being constructed in Latin America by feminists and others around the Andean con- cept of Buen Vivir; and lastly post-development visions forAfrica (anticipating Development 55.4). The Local/Global Encounters section reports on how feminists are resisting inequitable economic processes on the ground. The articles underline women’s rights defenders’ economic and social struggles in the regional and national context. Whether on the streets in the US Occupy move- ment, or in Arab squares, or protesting at shock therapy in Greece or indigenous women defend- ing their territories ^ the authors speak of passion and courage, as well as pain. The concluding photo essay captures in images the breadth of emotions and sheer diversity of women (and men) attending the AWID Forum. None of these themes and issues will be entirely new to Development readers who will recognize that this journal issue is a continuation of many of the journal’s editorial concerns. Since 2008 (and earlier), Development has been assessing and questioning the crisis in economics, exploring concepts like food sovereignty, sustaining liveli- hoods, climate justice, cosmovisions, Buen Vivir, civic action and the green economy. Even given that many contributors to those issues spoke of gender equality and women’s rights, true to Development’s editorial line, specific issues need to be devoted to deepening an understanding of gender power relations in development. As very recent events show, women’s rights and gender equality continues to be under threat. I am writing this as the results of the Egyptian election are coming in, with a win to Mohamed Morsi of the Muslim Brotherhood along with cheers of Islamists in Tahrir Square. I wonder what the young Egyptian women whom I listened to at the AWID Forum are feeling. The aftermath of the Arab Spring has not been inclusive of the women who came out on the streets16 months ago. I am also writing at the conclusion of the United Nations Conference on Sustainable Development Rioþ20 with its messy and disappointing end. Kumi Naidoo of Greenpeace has declared it a cata- strophe. Certainly the women attending were appalled.2 The official declaration called ‘The Future We Want’ signed by 190 countries only ‘recalls’ (not recognizes) the Beijing Declaration in 1995. And any reference to support sexuality, reproductive rights and health was repressed, at the instigation of the Vatican and conservative states. Suchan outcome takes women’s rights back two decades. These losses for women’s rights and body poli- tics underline that it is vital that all of us under- stand that gender equality and women’s rights are crucial to democracy and sustainable livelihoods, to the planet’s health and to all of our future. It is too much to hope that the AWID Forum and this resulting set of excellent articles alone will keep the energy and passion we require to ensure a secure and safe future. Feminists and women’s rights defenders cannot do it for themselves, whatever the Annie Lennox and Aretha Franklin song (Sisters Are Doin’ It For Themselves) promises.What we need is for all peo- ple concerned about economic and social justice and development to be informed and knowledge- able on women’s rights within the context of economic and the whole breadth of today’s climate, food, energy and care crises.Women need to deal with economic issues from their own experience, in their own language and concerns and those experiences need to be brought to the table, as Ghosh says ^ feminists need to be actively engaged in the urgent task of finding alternatives. Development 55(3): Upfront 258 The journal abounds with vision and under- standing of what is required ^ the question will be how to ensure dialogue goes beyond the AWID Forum to reach others ^ so that gender equity is part of future social movement strategies, new forms of development policy and democratic change. The tweets, blogs and immediate report- ing via‘Open Democracy’, popular radio, television and alternative media meant that the highlights, individual peoples’ impressions and key messages went out immediately to tens of thousands of people. But building alliances is much harder. So how to break out of the comfort zone of the AWID Forum? That does not mean that such Forums should not be (especially ones that are so well organized, are held in seven languages and engage so many diverse people). These spaces are vital, given that the world is decidedly not a comfortable place for most attending ^ the transgender people, the sex workers, domestic workers, rape survivors, those living with disabil- ities, indigenous women, all of whom are strug- gling for their rights on many levels. But we need to work hard to make connections that reach out from such events and processes in order to build open inclusive spaces, networks and pathways towards economic justice. These alliances need to be built from strategic dialogues, joint action and political engagement that should be at the basis of true democratic engagement that confronts our current injustice economic and social power structures. Notes 1 TheAWID Forum held in Bangkok:‘Women’s Rights in Development’, Development 49(1), (January 2006);TheAWID Forum held in CapeTown:‘Power, Movements, Change’, Development 52(2), (June 2009). 2 See the Women’s Major Group press release: http://www.wecf.eu/english/press/releases/2012/06/womenstatement- outcomesRio.php. Harcourt: Upfront 259 work_hqwjal4q5bdp3ejn2jhk4uk4ne ---- AMS Skip to main content Menu AMS Open Search Close Search Search the site: Main navigation (extended config) Academics+ Program Learning Outcomes Major Minor Current Course Offerings Academic Year Course Offering AMS Program+ Why be an AMS Major? Alumni People+ Faculty Lecturers Emeritus Faculty Staff Student+ Advising Emphasis Plan Senior Capstone Internship Prizes Transfer Students Letters of Recommendation Resources for Students AMS AT 50+ American Studies at UC Davis: Breaking Down Walls for 50 Years CAREN KAPLAN RETIREMENT SYMPOSIUM         Welcome! Founded during the 1968-69 school year, American Studies Department at UC Davis stands apart as the only department of its kind in the University of California system. In its 50 + years on campus it has been dedicated to creating an interdisciplinary space for students to connect their personal curiosities and concerns to broader public issues, histories, and materials.  What is American Studies? When you hear the phrase "American Studies," you might think of classrooms decked out in red, white, and blue; classes that feel just like your 10th grade U.S. history class; and images of Uncle Sam and Captain America. If you walk through our wing on the second floor of Hart Hall, you'll see that's not the case. The American Studies Department at Davis (AMS at UCD) looks at American culture as a compilation of things that can be questioned and analyzed. And it uses many lenses to understand the complicated, messy, and diverse lives people live in both in the United States and in an interconnected world. As an interdisciplinary department, AMS at UCD pulls from several disciplines (history, literature, environmental science, food science, sociology, and more) to explore phenomena in and related to U.S. culture. The faculty study food, prisons, the environment, artificial sweeteners, music, militarized culture, and much more. Each of them asks questions and teaches classes to help all of us make sense of the world we live in. So, in American Studies classes at Davis, you'll find folks asking questions about drones, thinking about the boom of diversity in comics, studying the California rodeo, analyzing the role of gossip in specific communities, wondering what needs to happen to save our planet, how to tie social science justice and academic research, and more.  Why study American Studies at Davis?  AMS at UCD has spent the last 50+ years grappling with questions of American-ness. The department isn't afraid to shy away from the personal and the political. You'll find that many of our faculty study topics that are near and dear to their hearts. AMS at UCD is a place for rigorous study and "making sense" of what's important to you. It's a place to ask big (and sometimes hard and scary) questions to better understand the world. American Studies Association Statement on BLM & Rebellion of 2020 Asian American Studies Association Statement on Atlanta Why be an American Studies Major? Our alumni are now lawyers, teachers, social workers, urban planners, marketing professionals, software engineers, filmmakers, professors, professional writers (and comedians) and non-profit staff and leaders. If this appeals to you, you might fit well in our community. If you have questions or curiosities about the diverse cultures that make up the U.S., AMS at UCD might be for you. If you want individualized attention, a major that lets you explore multiple disciplines, and the chance to study topics that are important to you, take a class with us or reach out to our major advisor and our undergraduate faculty advisor.  Contact Us Visit our advising office at 1203 Hart Hall (First floor). Closed due to COVID-19. Email general inquiries to ams-advising@ucdavis.edu. To contact individual faculty, see faculty listing. Call the American Studies office at 530-752-6429. Social Media Links Main Office 1203 Hart Hall (First floor) University of California, Davis  One Shields Avenue  Davis, CA 95616  Contact Us Visit our advising office at 1203 Hart Hall (First floor).  Email general inquiries to ams-advising@ucdavis.edu. To contact individual faculty, see faculty listing. Call the American Studies office at 530-752-6429. Join our Facebook group for news and announcements. Admin Links Login Webmaster UC Davis College of Letters and Science | Social Sciences and Humanities Building | 530-752-0394 University of California, Davis, One Shields Avenue, Davis, CA 95616 | 530-752-1011 Questions or comments? Privacy & Accessibility Principles of Community University of California Sitemap Last update: March 22, 2021 Copyright © The Regents of the University of California, Davis campus. All rights reserved. This site is officially grown in SiteFarm. work_hr4qb3hxcvbdldw32sxonq4clu ---- Injustice in the Justice System: Reforming Inequities for True “Justice for All” UC Santa Barbara UC Santa Barbara Previously Published Works Title Injustice in the Justice System: Reforming Inequities for True "Justice for All" Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/5cx8s78s Journal COUNSELING PSYCHOLOGIST, 47(5) ISSN 0011-0000 Authors Varghese, Femina P Israel, Tania Seymour, Guy et al. Publication Date 2019-07-01 DOI 10.1177/0011000019892329 Peer reviewed eScholarship.org Powered by the California Digital Library University of California https://escholarship.org/uc/item/5cx8s78s https://escholarship.org/uc/item/5cx8s78s#author https://escholarship.org http://www.cdlib.org/ https://doi.org/10.1177/0011000019892329 The Counseling Psychologist 2019, Vol. 47(5) 682 –740 © The Author(s) 2019 Article reuse guidelines: sagepub.com/journals-permissions DOI: 10.1177/0011000019892329 journals.sagepub.com/home/tcp 50th Anniversary Commemoration Injustice in the Justice System: Reforming Inequities for True “Justice for All” Femina P. Varghese1 , Tania Israel2, Guy Seymour3, Rachel Becker Herbst4,5, Lauren G. Suarez6, and Candice Hargons7 Abstract True justice is equitable. Counseling psychologists, through their skills, knowledge, and values, can be a powerful force in reforming a system that oppresses marginalized groups to one that is just. In this paper, we focus on three major aspects of the justice system: laws and the courts, law enforcement, and detention and corrections, and we further describe injustice in these three areas. We then use critical race theory and counseling psychology perspectives to develop a framework to provide counseling psychologists with practical strategies to transform inequities. Such strategies include advocating to change unjust laws, filling the research gap for effective and humane practices, developing evidence-based programs, and providing leadership and training. Keywords race, undocumented immigrants, police, sex trafficking, crime 1University of Central Arkansas, Conway, AR, USA 2University of California, Santa Barbara, Santa Barbara, CA, USA 3Psicólogo Clínico y Forense Intercultural Hispano, Decatur, GA, USA 4Cincinnati Children’s Hospital Medical Center, Cincinnati, OH, USA 5University of Cincinnati, Cincinnati, OH, USA 6Bruce W. Carter Miami VA Medical Center, Miami, FL, USA 7University of Kentucky, Lexington, USA Corresponding Author: Femina P. Varghese, University of Central Arkansas, Department of Psychology and Counseling, Box 4915, Conway, AR 72035-0001, USA. Email: fvarghese@uca.edu 892329TCPXXX10.1177/0011000019892329The Counseling PsychologistVarghese et al. research-article2019 https://us.sagepub.com/en-us/journals-permissions https://journals.sagepub.com/home/tcp mailto:fvarghese@uca.edu http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1177%2F0011000019892329&domain=pdf&date_stamp=2019-12-16 Varghese et al. 683 Each time a man stands up for an ideal, or acts to improve the lot of others, or strikes out against injustice, he sends forth a tiny ripple of hope, and crossing each other from a million different centers of energy and daring, those ripples build a current that can sweep down the mightiest walls of oppression and resistance. —Robert F. Kennedy, Day of Affirmation Address Administer true justice; show mercy and compassion to one another. —Zechariah 7:9, NIV From police use of excessive force to separating children from parents at the border, injustice in the justice system has garnered media attention (e.g., Benner, 2019; Jordan, 2019) and sparked public outrage (e.g., “Black lives upended by policing,” 2018; Ramsey, 2019). For People of Color, this injus- tice is particularly distressing (Bor, Venkataramani, Williams, & Tsai, 2018). For example, unarmed People of Color have experienced unnecessary vio- lence by law enforcement personnel, with law enforcement personnel rarely held accountable (Stinson, 2017). Youth of Color are disproportionately detained (Hockenberry & Puzzanchera, 2018) and disproportionately tried as adults (Juszkiewicz, 2007). Blacks comprise just 13.4% of the U.S. popula- tion (U.S. Census Bureau, 2017) but account for 33.0% of those incarcerated in state and federal prisons (Gramlich, 2018). In comparison, Whites com- prise 76.6% of the U.S. population, but account for 30.0% of the state and federal inmate population (Gramlich, 2018; U.S. Census Bureau, 2017). Our goal for justice system reform is an equitable system that upholds human rights and the dignity of people regardless of background. This goal is consistent with counseling psychology perspectives that emphasize social justice and cultural competence (see Altmaier & Hansen, 2012). Additionally, we acknowledge that inequities of the justice system reflect and reify the inequities in our larger society. We cannot fully resolve the problems in our justice system without dismantling racism and other forms of oppression in our society, but neither can we wait until we dismantle all forms of oppres- sion to address the oppression that resides in the justice system. Our aim for this manuscript is to elucidate strategies to maximize justice within the exist- ing system as we strive for more comprehensive societal reform. Throughout this manuscript, we primarily refer to distributive justice—the “fair and equitable allocation of resources, burdens, pains, and gains” (see Prilleltensky, 2014, p. 296)—and procedural justice, which focuses on how decisions are made about justice and who participates in decision-making 684 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) about what is just. Inherent in this definition are requisite components of jus- tice, including whether individuals affected by decisions have been treated with fairness and included in the decision-making process (Prilleltensky, 2014). This 50th Anniversary issue of The Counseling Psychologist occurs 50 years after the assassination of two voices for justice, Martin Luther King, Jr. and Robert F. Kennedy. Yet, inequitable practices still permeate the U.S. justice sys- tem. Like Martin Luther King, Jr. and Robert F. Kennedy, we believe that justice is a human right. Reforming the system presents many challenges, including filling the research gap in justice reform issues, disseminating research about prevention and cultural competence, educating the public on justice reform issues, and developing effective relationships to transform societal structures. We encourage counseling psychologists to utilize their skills, knowledge, and values toward justice reform to create a just society for all people. Alongside the lens of counseling psychology, which we describe next, we use critical race theory (CRT; Delgado & Stefancic, 2017) as a framework to understand and approach justice system reform, given the salience of racial discrepancies within the justice system. CRT aligns with multiculturalism and advocacy goals and helps frame the potential role of counseling psy- chologists in justice system reform. CRT is particularly suitable for this dis- cussion, as the theory was developed within the legal system and focuses on reforming unjust societal systems, with iterations for Latinx (LatCrit), sexual minorities, and other oppressed marginalized groups (Delgado & Stafancic, 2017). Further, given the theory’s emphasis on the historical and current dis- proportionate rates of injustice among People of Color (Delgado & Stefancic, 2017), CRT aligns well with the aims of this paper. CRT CRT burgeoned in the 1970s to describe the racism jeopardizing the civil rights of People of Color, and as an answer to varied conceptualizations of the issue of racism (Crenshaw, 2011; Delgado & Stefancic, 2017). CRT provides a systemic understanding of racism, intersectionality, power, and oppression. It is comprised of core tenets focused on understanding racism and social action, where the latter is seen as a tool to reform society (Delgado & Stefancic, 2017). Crenshaw (2011) argued that CRT encourages a transdisci- plinary critique of the postracial society, and this article follows that recom- mendation by synthesizing the literature on law and criminal justice with that of counseling psychology and education. An overarching tenet of CRT is that racism is a normative, common expe- rience among People of Color, and that it is difficult to eradicate because it is embedded in the routine operations of U.S. society. Faith in “meritocracy” Varghese et al. 685 and “color-blindness” masks the most obvious forms of racism (Delgado & Stefancic, 2017) CRT argues for equitable treatment of all people to combat subtle forms of racism prevalent in society. A second tenet of CRT, as pro- posed by Delgado and Stefancic (2017), presents the lens that because racism serves to benefit White people, there would likely be less motivation for White people to end racism. The third tenet states that race (e.g., physical features such as skin color) is a social construct and invention of society, as there is no evidence of the biological underpinnings of the concept of race. Another tenet of the theory asserts that the privileged group may view the oppressed group differently depending on the era. For example, immigrant Muslims might be initially viewed as exotic, but once feared, could then be viewed as dangers to society to be hated (Delgado & Stefancic, 2017). The fifth tenet of CRT argues that no person has a single identity and encourages the study of intersectionality, multiple identities, and diversity within racial and/or ethnic groups (Crenshaw, 1991; Delgado & Stefancic, 2017; Moradi & Grzanka, 2017). This is important given that racism operates alongside and in conjunction with other systems of oppression such as clas- sism, sexism, heterosexism, ableism, and nativism. A key consideration of intersectionality is that the experiences of those with multiple marginalized identities (e.g., Black women) cannot be fully understood if each identity is examined independently. For example, Women of Color who are victimized experience unique structural barriers that exacerbate stressors—such as pov- erty, unemployment, and low social capital—as a result of being both a woman and a Person of Color (Crenshaw, 1991). Finally, CRT stresses the value of understanding the life experiences of People of Color when studying racially divided social positions, and in par- ticular the importance of understanding individuals’ distinctive stories in conceptualizing race and racism within political, social, and historical set- tings. Any efforts toward social justice require explicit attention to racism and its connections to other systems of oppression (Delgado & Stefancic, 2017). As we discuss in each section that follows, CRT provides a framework to understand the societal role in oppressing People of Color through laws, enforcement of laws, and how punishment is levied. Counseling psycholo- gists’ efforts to make the justice system more just will be incomplete if racism is not explicitly addressed. Psychology Framework for Justice System Advocacy The field of counseling psychology reflects a unique set of values, including cultural competence, social justice, and prevention (Altmaier & Hansen, 2012). 686 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) Notably, values related to CRT, such as the importance of understanding sys- temic barriers, and the use of social justice advocacy, are becoming increasingly prominent in the field (Lichtenberg, Hutman, & Goodyear, 2018). Motivated by such values, counseling psychologists are well positioned to tackle the chal- lenges of the justice system. As witnesses to outcomes of injustice and equipped with interpersonal skills, counseling psychologists are in a position to collabo- rate with, and advocate for, those who are most negatively impacted by the jus- tice system. Guided by CRT, counseling psychology skills can be used to advance meaningful advocacy efforts. Allied mental health professionals have articulated how to apply values and skills to advocacy efforts. For example, the American Counseling Association’s Advocacy Competency Domains (Toporek & Daniels, 2018) conceptualize advocacy in terms of (a) the level of intervention (microlevel to macrolevel), (b) the extent of client involvement (in collaboration with vs. on behalf of), and (c) the focus of counselor energy (from client support to system interventions). Envisioning the role of counseling psychologists in promoting justice within the justice system, we developed a framework that focuses on the macrolevel and system intervention aspects of advocacy, drawing on psychologists’ strengths in research and intervention. Specifically, our framework, titled Framework for Justice System Advocacy (Table 1) identifies ways in which counseling psychologists can apply their skills to generate, interpret, and disseminate knowledge, as well as take action based Table 1. Framework for Justice System Advocacy Targets of Efforts Types of Efforts Policy makers Policy and system implementers Individuals affected by policies and systems Public Generate knowledge Conduct policy relevant research Evaluate interventions, policy, and practice Investigate experiences of those affected by injustice Study public perceptions and attitudes that perpetuate injustice Interpret and disseminate knowledge Share knowledge with policy makers and courts Conduct professional development and consultation with justice system employees Empower communities with knowledge Inform the public Take action based on evidence, skills, and values Make policy Advance implementation of evidence-based practice Engage in targeted community prevention and intervention efforts Engage in universal prevention and intervention efforts Varghese et al. 687 on evidence, skills, and values. Counseling psychologists may focus their skills to work with those who develop, implement, or are particularly influ- enced by policy related to the justice system, and also to work with the gen- eral public. Ideally, this framework will help counseling psychologists align their interests, skills, and connections with specific types of advocacy to pro- mote justice in the justice system. Consistent with our aim of providing an actionable mission for counseling psychologists to promote justice, we focus on three major aspects of the justice system: laws and the courts, law enforcement, and corrections and detention. These are three large structures in society foundational to distributive and pro- cedural justice, and provide the context in which People of Color face injustice within the justice system. Grounded on CRT and counseling psychology per- spectives, we specifically endeavor to (a) identify areas within the justice sys- tem in need of reform; (b) present strategies for counseling psychologists’ potential roles in justice system reform; and (c) highlight implications for clini- cal practice, research, education, and advocacy in justice system reform. Laws and the Courts Racialized Laws: Past and Present According to CRT, it is important to examine historical, social, political, and economic contexts when developing an understanding of racial stratification in U.S. society (Delgado & Stefancic, 2017); these contexts also influence differential outcomes in the justice system for People of Color. Consider, for example, a recently discontinued U.S. policy of separating migrant families at the Southern border. This mirrors other historical laws and policies in the United States (Pryce, 2018). For example, slavery separated children from mothers for profit (Pryce, 2018). “Black Codes” separated Black men from their families through arrest and incarceration (Blackmon, 2009). Boarding schools separated Native American children from families for forced assimi- lation (see Gone et al., 2019; Pryce, 2018). Other laws demonstrate continual injustice for People of Color. During World War II, over 110,000 Japanese living in the United States were forced to relocate to internment camps (see Nagata, Kim, & Wu, 2019). During the Great Depression, it has been esti- mated that up to 1,000,000 Mexican immigrants and U.S. citizens of Mexican ancestry were coerced to leave the country (U.S. Citizenship and Immigration Services, 2014). Deportations took place even in hospital emergency rooms, leading to community trauma, as some U.S. citizens of Latinx descent con- tinue to avoid accessing emergency health care for fear of deportation (Maldonado, Rodriguez, Torres, Flores, & Lovato, 2013). 688 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) Even some laws that do not explicitly dictate discriminatory procedures based on race still disproportionately and negatively influence People of Color. For example, under Presidents Richard Nixon and Ronald Reagan, the federal government initiated and escalated the War on Drugs, which dispro- portionately criminalized drugs used and sold primarily by Persons of Color (Hinton, 2016). U.S. laws enacted after the terrorist attacks of September 11, 2001, increased the deportation and detainment of immigrants (Roth, 2005). Further, and in conflict with international law, torture strategies (e.g., water- boarding) were employed on detained Muslims, many of whom were from Arab or South Asian countries, and who were suspected, even without evi- dence of guilt, of terroristic associations (Barak, Leighton, & Cotton, 2015; Senate Select Committee on Intelligence, 2014). Today, laws continue to have a differential application for People of Color. On June 26, 2018, the U.S. Supreme Court upheld a ban that prevented entry to the United States by people from five Muslim majority nations—Iran, Libya, Somalia, Syria, and Yemen (Trump, President of the United States v. Hawaii, 2018). Other laws allow law enforcement personnel to stop anyone even suspected of having an undocumented status (Williams, 2011). Further, the U.S. Department of Justice (U.S. DOJ) reported that law enforcement has been used to systematically extract money from the poorest residents of cities (e.g., residents in Ferguson, Missouri; U.S. DOJ, 2015). Other laws have been differentially applied to People of Color, even if not developed to be intentionally racist. For example, “Stand Your Ground” laws allow civilians to use deadly force for self or property protection (National Conference of State Legislatures, 2018). According to Florida law: (1) A person who is in a dwelling or residence in which the person has a right to be has no duty to retreat and has the right to stand his or her ground and use or threaten to use: (a) Nondeadly force against another when and to the extent that the per- son reasonably believes that such conduct is necessary to defend him- self or herself or another against the other’s imminent use of unlawful force; or (b) Deadly force if he or she reasonably believes that using or threatening to use such force is necessary to prevent imminent death or great bodily harm to himself or herself or another or to prevent the immi- nent commission of a forcible felony (Justifiable Use of Force, 2019). An analysis of convictions based on Florida’s “Stand Your Ground” laws found that, if the victim was White, a conviction of guilt for using deadly Varghese et al. 689 force was twice as likely than if the victim was not White (Ackerman, Goodman, Gilbert, Arroyo-Johnson, & Pagano, 2015). Sentencing and Fees Sentencing. Laws that influence sentencing can also create inequities in the justice system, and such laws can disproportionately affect People of Color. For example, “Mandatory Minimum Sentencing” laws require judges to give predetermined sentences for crimes regardless of context. Thus, having 5 grams of methamphetamine requires a sentence of at least 5 years of prison (Criminal Justice Policy Foundation, 2018). Crack cocaine, which is predomi- nantly used by the Black community, has a mandatory minimum of 5 years for 28 grams. On the other hand, powder cocaine, which is similar to crack cocaine but lacks baking soda, is used primarily by Whites, and has a mandatory mini- mum of 5 years for 500 grams (U.S. Sentencing Commission, 2017b). Thus, these sentencing guidelines can disproportionately affect People of Color. Further, the death penalty is legal in 31 states, with Blacks encompassing 41.5% of all people on death row (Criminal Justice Project, 2017), despite the fact that Blacks account for only 13.4% of the U.S. population (U.S. Census Bureau, 2017). Similarly, the U.S. Sentencing Commission (2017a) found that, controlling for relevant factors such as type of crime, Black men are given sentence lengths 19.1% longer than White men. There is also a strong potential for bias to arise in the jury selection process, as jurors are selected from lists that often underrepresent People of Color such as vehicle registra- tions, voter registrations, and property tax rolls (see Walker, Spohn, & Delone, 2018). Judges may also hold biases. In an empirical study with 239 federal and state judges (29% women), results suggested that judges held implicit bias and prejudice against People of Color and religious minorities (Levinson, Bennett, & Hioki, 2017). Attempts to ameliorate bias, such as computerized methods of sentencing, may also be problematic, as the data for computer algorithms may themselves be biased, such as arrest data that fail to account for enhanced police surveillance in areas populated by People of Color or data from sources that may not be methodologically sound (Hannah- Moffatt, 2018). One such algorithm had a much higher rate of false positives in predicting recidivism for Blacks (40.4% false positives) than for Whites (25.4% false positives; Dressel & Farid, 2018). More effective strategies to decrease sentencing bias are needed that address root causes and promote procedural justice. Fees. Although public safety should be the reason for court involvement, fines and fees (e.g., as administrative add-ons to traffic tickets) often provide 690 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) revenue to the court and local government. However, the collection of fees is a separate issue from public safety and could present a conflict of interest (Case & Bhattacharya, 2017). Indeed, public safety may worsen with fines and fees, as youth punished with fines and fees are more likely to recidivate (Piquero & Jennings, 2016). In many states, not paying a fine for a traffic violation leads to higher fees, yet people who are poor often struggle to pay fees that range from $100 to $300 (Case & Battacharya, 2017). In evaluating the police and court system in Ferguson, Missouri for just the year 2013, the Justice Department found that although the city had a population of 21,135 residents, 32,975 warrants for arrests were issued, mainly for traffic-related offenses (Schwartztol, 2017). In addition, most of the courts in St. Louis, MO, give high fines for traffic citations and other misdemeanor offenses, disproportionately burdening individuals with lower socio-economic status and threatening their ability to obtain and retain employment (“Policing and Profit,” 2015). Physical and Mental Health Consequences of Biased Laws and its Application A foundational principle of U.S. democracy, stated clearly in the U.S. Declaration of Independence, is that government powers are derived from the consent of the governed. Such powers include establishing laws and policies. Thus, it can be considered that biased laws and courts may reflect similarly biased societal beliefs and attitudes toward targeted groups. Societal discrimi- nation appears to have physical and mental health consequences, as meta- analytic reviews found that perceived discrimination and racism negatively affected physical and mental health (Carter, Lau, Johnson, & Kirkinis, 2017; Lee & Ahn, 2011; Pascoe & Richman, 2009). Although more empirical evi- dence for a direct relationship between biased laws and health is needed, given the history of U.S. policies and laws that have treated People of Color in an unjust manner, the findings of the aforementioned meta-analyses might pro- vide at least a partial explanation for why People of Color not only have the highest incarceration rates but also the worst health outcomes, including the highest rates of infant mortality, the highest rates of mortality associated with diabetes, and the highest mortality rates before age 75 (Bailey et al., 2017). CRT posits that racism is pervasive throughout the structures of society, extending beyond the laws and the courts. Laws need to be enforced, yet unjust laws have had a disproportionate application on People of Color, often creating incentives and an infrastructure that leads law enforcement person- nel to focus disproportionately on these communities (U.S. DOJ, Civil Rights Division, 2015). Thus, the next section provides further discussion about the Varghese et al. 691 enforcement of laws, community reactions to their enforcement, and issues in law enforcement training and intervention. Law Enforcement Police shootings of unarmed Black men have evoked national attention (Hargons et al., 2017). CRT emphasizes a systemic understanding of such racial injustice by focusing on the perspectives of the oppressed group, and endorses the enactment of change through advocacy. This section extends the CRT framework to provide information on the racially unjust state of U.S. law enforcement, community perceptions of law enforcement, and ongoing initiatives to address injustices. Police Violence, Racial Profiling, and Discrimination Against People of Color The proliferation of incidents where unarmed People of Color—such as Blacks, Latinx, Native Americans, and Asians—have been seriously injured or killed, have led to increased efforts for more careful oversight of law enforcement personnel, including efforts for greater transparency in the supervision and reporting of police activities (see Police Executive Research Forum, 2015). Among rates of people killed by police in 2016, out of every 1,000,000 individuals, Native Americans were killed at the highest rate at 10.13 persons, followed by Blacks at 6.64, and Latinx at 3.23, whereas Whites and Asians/Pacific Islanders were killed at rates of 2.9 and 1.17, respectively (Swaine & McCarthy, 2017). The National Institute of Justice (2011) has identified problematic policies and strategies in the use of force by law enforcement personnel. In many instances, the use of Oleoresin Capsicum (pepper spray) and electronic con- trol weapons (e.g., stun guns, tasers) has been included routinely under defi- nitions of “police brutality,” or has been used to illustrate the use of excessive force (National Institute of Justice, 2011). The proliferation of cameras, from those in cellular phones to body cameras worn by police, to store-bought video cameras, allows for an even greater awareness of racial disparities in policing (Dreier, 2016). For example, when reporting on the court record of a fatal police shooting in 2014, the Dayton News stated that John Crawford III was shot to death by law enforcement personnel in a Walmart store due to concerns that a Black man was loading and pointing a gun at people in the store. However, store video revealed that the customer had not pointed a gun at anyone but was looking at the shelf while nonchalantly swinging a Walmart BB gun (Gokavi, 2016). 692 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) The “Veil of Darkness” analytic method, one of the most data-driven methods for examining racial differences in the pattern of police traffic stops, compares traffic stops in daylight with stops in the evening (Ross, Fazzalaro, Barone, & Kalinowski, 2016). Ross et al. (2016) found that People of Color were more likely than their White counterparts to be stopped during the day, when the driver’s race was visible, than at night when race was less visible. In addition, a comprehensive investigative report on the city of Ferguson revealed that city officials routinely urged the police chief to generate more revenue through enforcement of traffic laws and local ordinances, even when legitimate violations had not taken place (U.S. DOJ, Civil Rights Division, 2015). This mandate profoundly influenced the Ferguson Police Department’s relationship with the community, as officers seemed to view some residents, especially those in Black and poor neighborhoods, less as constituents to be protected than as prey for potential sources of revenue (U.S. DOJ, Civil Rights Division, 2015). These unjust practices were so egregious that the city was mandated to develop a court-supervised consent agreement with the U.S. Justice Department’s Office of Civil Rights (U.S. v. City of Ferguson, 2016 This consent agreement committed the municipality (e.g., city or district) to appoint and pay for a federally authorized monitor of the agreement, actually a one- or two-person office with associated staff who would have court-mandated oversight of all police operations, includ- ing the task of reviewing and supervising critical incidents, especially use- of-force events. The monitor, as per the agreement, must support wide-ranging involvement of community members, including the development of com- mittees of residents who provide input about the way in which the Ferguson Police Department is run. Data collected through this initiative, including use-of-force incidents, vehicle searches conducted pursuant to traffic stops, and other elements of enforcement actions, were required by the consent agreements to be made available to the federal monitor, including the rea- sons for taking those actions (see U.S. v. City of Cleveland, 2015; U.S. v. City of Ferguson, 2016). Because the consent agreement gave the monitor over- sight of the Ferguson Police Department, local government officials resisted the change but were obligated to abide by it by the Federal Court (see U.S. v. City of Cleveland, 2015; U.S. v. City of Ferguson, 2016). Although the experiences of Men of Color are highlighted in popular media, Black women also experience disparities in policing. Black women are more likely than White and Latina women to experience traffic stops as well as arrests during stops (Prison Policy Initiative, 2019). For example, video footage of Sandra Bland, a Black woman stopped by police for a sim- ple traffic violation, shows the officer violently throwing her to the ground and threatening her with “I will light you up!” for refusing to put out her Varghese et al. 693 cigarette (Ford, 2015). In 2013, of all women stopped by police in New York City, 53.4% were Black, and 27.5% were Latina, but only 13.4% were White (as reported in Crenshaw, Ritchie, Anspach, Gilmer, & Harris, 2015). South Asians have also experienced use of excessive force and unjust treatment by police (e.g., American Civil Liberties Union [ACLU] of New York, 2019; Patel v. City of Madison, 2018; Sikh American Legal Education Defense Fund, 2007). For example, a 57-year-old Asian Indian man, Sureshbhai Patel, was visiting his son, an engineer, in Madison, AL. While walking in the neighborhood where his son lived, a law enforcement officer approached and questioned Mr. Patel because the officer had received a call regarding an unfamiliar “skinny Black man” in the neighborhood. Mr. Patel was unable to speak English, and with the few English words he knew, stated multiple times “India” and “no English” to the officer. The officer did not appear to pay attention to the statements, however, and during the pat down threw Patel, who weighed 115-lbs. and was unarmed, to the ground with such a violent force, that it caused severe spinal injury and paralysis in the Indian man. The officer claimed that Mr. Patel did not listen to him and jerked away—although video evidence did not indicate that any such movement occurred (Patel v. City of Madison, 2018). Despite the video evidence, the officer did not lose his job and the assault charges for the officer were dropped, as the judge (a White female) stated that the officer’s guilt could not be proven beyond a reasonable doubt (see Fuchs, 2016). In addition to racial minorities, individuals with disabilities have dispro- portionately experienced police use of force. The Treatment Advocacy Center (2015) investigated three different databases, one from 2011 and two from 2015, and discovered that 25% of people killed by law enforcement person- nel had a cognitive disability or mental health diagnosis, including many high profile cases involving People of Color (e.g., Eric Garner, Sandra Bland; Perry & Carter-Long, 2016). The U.S. Department of Health and Human Services (2017) reported that, compared to the general population, having a significant mental illness increased the probability to be the victims of violent crime tenfold, and the mentally ill were responsible for 3% to 5% of violent crimes. Use of force toward people with a disability further underscores the need for transformation in the justice system. There is a need to understand “where disability intersects with other factors that often lead to police vio- lence” (Perry & Carter-Long, 2016, p. 1). Community Perspectives People of Color. Systemic injustices, perceptions, and experiences of police– community interactions differ based on the race and/or ethnicity of the 694 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) community members. Numerous studies have demonstrated that Black and Latinx community members report lower trust of law enforcement officers than their White counterparts (e.g., Brunson & Miller, 2006; Solis, Portillo, & Brunson, 2009). Brunson and Miller (2006) interviewed 40 Black youth aged 13 to 19 years in St. Louis, to explore their perceptions of law enforce- ment. Most participants stated that they had or experienced (83%) harass- ment by law enforcement personnel. Some participants reported that law enforcement officers did not arrive quickly when called for help, and when participants were charged with crimes, law enforcement officers acted more forcefully and violently than necessary. A study in Miami presented similar results (Ruffin, 2017), indicating that 82% of the respondents perceived that race and social class were the biggest reasons for the poor interactions between the police and the community. A qualitative study of 30 Puerto Rican and Dominican young adults in New York’s Spanish Harlem sug- gested “unfavorable views of local police, concerns about the amount of time it takes for officers to arrive when summoned, and officers’ routine disre- spect of community members during involuntary police citizen encounters” (Solis et al., 2009, pp. 44–45). Variability in experiences may occur across groups and cities. For exam- ple, a survey of 850 Arab Americans in Detroit indicated that most partici- pants endorsed confidence in the police (Sun & Wu, 2015). However, another study using community-based data indicated that the majority of Arab American participants did not support aggressive antiterrorist policing of Arab Americans (Sun, Wu, & Poteyeva, 2011). These findings suggest that within marginalized racial and ethnic groups, community perspectives on policing align with the community’s experiences of law enforcement. Given that Communities of Color also want to be protected and served, participants’ perspectives reflect both the desired role of law enforcement and lived expe- rience with law enforcement. This complex picture unpacks dichotomous notions of police and community relations in Communities of Color, and pro- vides a starting point for counseling psychologists to understand ways in which they may partner with both groups to reenvision the function of law enforcement in Communities of Color. LGBTQ communities. CRT tradition provides an analysis that focuses on race. However, injustices in the justice system may be directed at marginalized groups or at individuals whose marginalized identities intersect with racially marginalized identities, such as sexual and gender minorities (SGMs). Simi- lar to racial minorities, SGMs report experiencing biased treatment by law enforcement, such as officers’ reluctance to intervene in anti-LGBTQ public harassment, or their unwillingness to determine if a crime was motivated by Varghese et al. 695 hate (Israel et al., 2017). These perceptions may contribute to LGBTQ peo- ple’s mistrust of law enforcement personnel and reluctance to report crimes (Mallory, Hasenbush, & Sears, 2015). Further, law-enforcement culture reflects traditional masculinity and heteronormativity (Collins & Rocco, 2015), with evidence of hostility towards peers who are sexual-minority law enforcement officers (Lyons, DeValve, & Garner, 2008). In a large study of transgender Latinx women, most participants reported verbally abusive treatment by police, with 24% indicating sexual assault by police and 21% indicating physical assault (Mallory et al., 2015). Furthermore, laws that criminalize sexual behavior related to HIV status are used dispro- portionately against People of Color (Center for American Progress & Movement Advancement Project, 2016). Such disparities in the application of justice result in the intersectionality of oppression within the legal system, which mirrors societal inequities. Physical and Mental Health Consequences of Unjust Law Enforcement When suspects resist police authority or when law enforcement officers use force, the potential for injury increases. Police injured an estimated 55,400 people during stop-and-search incidents in 2012 (Miller et al., 2017). A study of 304 residents and 261 police officers in the Ferguson community found that Black residents experienced higher levels of depres- sion and PTSD than White residents; further, all residents in the sample, regardless of race, had higher symptoms of these disorders than law enforcement personnel (Galovski et al., 2016). The authors attributed Black residents’ high levels of distress to the community violence that ensued between community members and police following the death of Michael Brown, an unarmed Black youth shot to death by a White law enforcement officer. Similarly, Muslim Americans in the United States who experienced government or police surveillance reported higher levels of anxiety than Muslim Americans who had not interfaced with law enforcement personnel (O’Conner & Jahan, 2014). CRT emphasizes that racism is pervasive. Thus, the natural result of racial bias in laws, courts, and law enforcement is the subsequent over-representa- tion of People of Color and those with intersecting identities in corrections and detention centers. In the next section, corrections and detention are dis- cussed, focusing on those groups that are over-represented in youth and adult facilities. We also outline the specific roles that counseling psychologists can take in alleviating these disparities. 696 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) Detention and Corrections: Juveniles, Adults, Re-entry, and Special Populations One in 45 Whites is under correctional supervision, but the proportions are much higher for People of Color; one in 11 Blacks and one in 27 Latinx are under correctional supervision (Pew Center on the States, 2009). An analysis of 2014 data from the Bureau of Justice Statistics reported that Black women had 1.6 to 4.1 times more likelihood of incarceration than White women (Carson, 2015). Sexual minorities are significantly overrepresented amid those who are incarcerated, comprising 42.1% of all incarcerated women (Meyer et al., 2017). Of transgender women, nearly one in five (19.3%) expe- rienced incarceration, and 41.6% among these were transgender Women of Color (Reisner, Bailey, & Sevelius, 2014). Compared to other Western countries, the United States seems less focused on rehabilitation in general (Subramanian & Shames, 2013). When compar- ing U.S. prisons with prisons in Germany and Norway, results indicated that overall, those in Europe focused more on rehabilitation than those in the United States; U.S. prisons seemed more focused on punishment than reha- bilitation (Subramanian & Shames, 2013). Further, the growth in the use of private prisons in the United States (Gotsch & Basti, 2018), which have a profit-generating motive to incarcerate individuals, may constitute a conflict of interest. With an emphasis on profits, these prisons have little incentive to focus on rehabilitating prisoners or enhancing public safety. In the next sec- tion, we address issues related to the correctional system, such as detention populations and issues, adjudicated youth, youth trafficking, adult imprison- ment, and reentry into society. We conclude by discussing the growth of immigrants in federal detention facilities, with specific considerations for unaccompanied immigrant minors. Justice-Involved Youth Arrest and Detention. Youth of Color are overrepresented among youth arrested and detained (Krisberg, 2018), a concept widely known as dispro- portionate minority contact. National juvenile court statistics from 2015 indi- cate that more Black youth (28,400) were placed out of the home (e.g., detention) than their White counterparts (22,400; Hockenberry & Puzzanch- era, 2018). Further, Latinx youth were also more likely to be detained than Whites (Bonnie, Johnson, Chemers, & Schuck, 2013). This is problematic, as juvenile detentions are often perceived as “pipelines to prison” (Edelman, 2007, p. A43). In addition, Black and Latinx youth are more likely to be tried as adults than their White counterparts (Juszkiewicz, 2007). Gonzales (2016) Varghese et al. 697 reported on a study conducted by WNYC radio in which data obtained from New Jersey courts revealed that almost 90% of the youth tried as adults were Black or Latinx. Numerous factors contribute to this disproportionate minority contact, including structural disparities such as poverty, poor housing, poor nutrition, and harsher discipline in school for Youth of Color versus their White peers (see Bartol & Bartol, 2017; Bonnie et al., 2013). Structural disparities influ- ence criminal justice contact in a number of ways. For example, children in low-income, inner-city neighborhoods are exposed to high levels of lead, a potential risk factor for antisocial behavior (see Bartol & Bartol, 2017). In one study of young adults born to mothers living in older housing that had lead contamination, those who had higher arrest rates also had higher levels of blood lead concentration (Wright et al., 2008). Girls of Color are also overrepresented in the justice system. The National Women’s Law Center analyzed data from 2013 to 2014 from the U.S. Department of Education Office of Civil rights, and found that Black girls are 5.5 times more likely to experience suspension from school compared to White girls, and Native American and Latina girls are three times and two times, respectively, more likely to be suspended, illustrating how Girls of Color are placed at higher risk of justice system involvement (Onyeka- Crawford, Patrick, & Chaudhry, 2017). Using the same data set, researchers found that although Black girls comprise 15.6% of the school population, they constitute 37.3% of the girls arrested (Onyeka-Crawford et al., 2017). LGBT youth are overrepresented in the justice system as well, making up 20% of all juveniles; among these, 85% are Youth of Color (Center for American Progress, 2016). In one study, sexual minority youth reported experiencing harsher school discipline, and being more involved in the jus- tice system, than their nonsexual minority peers (Poteat, Scheer, & Chong, 2016). In a study of 55 LGBT youth involved with the justice system, over 90% of participants reported problems related to lack of parental support (Majd, Marksamer, & Reyes, 2009). In another study of sexual minority youth involved in the justice system, participants reported experiencing more sexual victimization than their heterosexual peers (Wilson et al., 2017) Child sex trafficking. Although many states have enacted legislation to protect victims of child sex trafficking, these youth continue to face increased risk of contact with the juvenile justice system (Polaris Project, 2013; Shared Hope International, 2016). The exact number of commercially sexually exploited children (CSEC) in the United States is difficult to determine, yet the U.S. Department of Justice estimates that at least 100,000 and up to 3,000,000 children are forced into prostitution, pornography, and/or sexual slavery 698 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) (Curtis et al., 2008). Covenant House (2013) found that approximately 25% of homeless youth receiving services at their shelter in New York were either trafficked or exchanged sex to have their basic needs met. Despite the fact that no certain figures exist, child advocates are concerned that the CSEC population is expanding due to Internet facilitation of trafficking and global- ization (Coonan & Thompson, 2003; Curtis et al., 2008). The Victims of Trafficking and Violence and Protection Act of 2000 defined severe forms of trafficking in persons as “a commercial sex act. . . induced by force, fraud or coercion or in which the person induced to perform such act is under 18 years of age” (§ 103-8). A commercial sex act refers to “any sex act, on account of which anything of value is given to or received by any person” (§ 103-8). Therefore, when a minor exchanges a sexual act for an item of value, this action meets the legal definition of sex trafficking whether the youth’s actions are believed to be coerced or voluntary (Covenant House, 2013; Finklea, Fernandes-Alcantara, & Siskin, 2015). Despite this legal pro- tection, many youth who engage in survival sex, or exchange sexual acts to acquire necessities such as food and shelter, risk criminalization or arrest (Lavoie, Dickerson, Redlich, & Quas, 2019). More recently, states have enacted “safe harbor” policies to increase the likelihood that CSEC will receive social welfare services rather than detention. Policing procedures and training vary widely, however, and in some states, CSEC are still legally allowed to be charged with prostitution (Lavoie et al., 2019). The American Psychological Association’s (APA) Report of the Task Force on Trafficking of Women and Girls (2014) noted that those at greatest risk for sex trafficking in the U.S. are vulnerable populations, including immigrants and People of Color (Clawson, Salomon, & Grace, 2008; Estes & Weiner, 2001). Further, emergent data suggests that Native American women and LGBT youth are at significantly higher risk of exploitation as compared to their White counterparts (Curtis et al., 2008; Deer, 2010). Risk factors for victimization include environmental conditions that disproportionately influ- ence low-income Communities of Color and Native populations, such as overcrowding, high rates of substance use and unemployment, and a thriving adult prostitution market (Deer, 2010; Estes & Weiner, 2001). In addition to environmental risk factors, individual risk factors include a history of child- hood trauma and interaction with the child welfare system (Gerassi, 2015). Externalizing behaviors often co-occur with risk factors for trafficking, lead- ing to increased risk of runaway behavior, truancy, and substance use (Landers, McGrath, Johnson, Armstrong, & Dollard, 2017). Specifically, a history of sexual abuse has been associated with greater likelihood of incar- ceration among girls, a phenomenon termed the “sexual abuse to prison pipe- line” (Saar, Epstein, Rosenthal, & Vafa, 2015, p. 5). Varghese et al. 699 Survivors of sex trafficking might come into contact with the justice sys- tem through a variety of pathways. Often, CSEC are initially arrested on sus- picion of prostitution or detained due to perceived involvement in delinquent behavior (Lavoie et al., 2019). Low-income Communities of Color may expe- rience higher rates of surveillance and legal punitive action, increasing the likelihood of individuals in those communities being detained following sex- ual exploitation (Sanghera, 2005). Of those engaging in survival sex in New York City, the majority are Youth of Color (Curtis et al., 2008). In one qualita- tive study examining the experiences of 283 LGBT youth engaging in survival sex, 37% identified as Black, 22% as Latinx, and 30% reported identifying with more than one race or ethnicity (Dank et al., 2015). Although there is a lack of research exploring rates of exploitation in Native communities, emer- gent data suggest that rates of sex trafficking are exceedingly high among Native American women (Deer, 2010). The literature points to an increased risk of trafficking among Women of Color due to economic and systemic bar- riers (Gerassi, 2015). As such, there is an increased likelihood that CSEC from marginalized communities will interact with the justice system. Adult Corrections The United States incarcerates more people than any other country in the world, with 49.3% of those incarcerated returning after release (U.S. Sentencing Commission, 2016). Mentally ill inmates are overrepresented in corrections (James & Glaze, 2006). According to a U.S. DOJ Bureau of Justice Statistics Special Report, in 2005 more than half of individuals in U.S. prisons and jails had a mental illness (James & Glaze, 2006). Scholars have found that 4% to 7% of the growth in incarceration between 1980 and 2000 was due to the deinstitutionalization of psychiatric hospitals (Raphael & Stoll, 2013). The use of private prisons run by for-profit companies has seen growth in the United States (Gotsch, & Basti, 2018). After comparing reports from the U.S. DOJ Bureau of Justice Statistics in 2000 and 2016, Gotsch and Basti (2018) of the Sentencing Project reported there has been a 47% increase in the private prison population, with a 442% increase in private detention centers for immi- grants, during this time. Having prisons that are in the business of generating profits could be a conflict of interest with rehabilitation efforts, given that profits are generated by housing people who are incarcerated, not by rehabilitating them for successful release. Further, such prisons are more violent and unsafe compared to government prisons (Office of Inspector General U.S. Department of Justice, 2016). For-profit prison companies generate several billion dollars in profits annually (Gotsch, & Basti, 2018). Lobbying efforts appear to be strong 700 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) by for-profit prison companies. For example, the ACLU of Montana (2017) reported that one for-profit prison entity, Core CIVIC, offered $30 million to the state’s governing administration to renew its private prison contract for another decade. An important part of best practices in correctional treatment to reduce recidivism, as noted in the risk need responsivity model (Bonta & Andrews, 2017), is for services to be tailored to the individual characteristics of the justice-involved person, such as race and ethnicity—a principle called responsivity (Bonta & Andrews, 2017). Correctly applying responsivity may be beneficial to encourage participation in prison programming for People of Color. For example, Rampey et al. (2016) of the U.S. Department of Education released a report indicating that Blacks, Latinx, and foreign-born persons have the lowest literacy and mathematical skills of all prisoners, and Blacks have the lowest rates of full-time employment history. Yet, Blacks were the least likely to receive training from college or trade school while in prison, as indicated by obtaining a certificate (Rampey et al., 2016). These compounded difficulties, coupled with racism, would continue the cycle of disadvantages in employment following release (Pager, 2003; Varghese, Hardin, Bauer, 2009). Relatedly, in an empirical investigation, researchers found that employers were less likely to call back Black men with a criminal record than their White counterparts, all other factors being equal (Pager, 2003). Undocumented Immigrants Immigrants comprise one of the fastest growing populations in the United States. It is estimated that 50% of U.S. foreign-born individuals are from Latin America (U.S. Census Bureau, 2017). A widely used term to describe immigrants who live in the United States without permitted admission by the government is undocumented. Research suggests that the intertwining of the criminal and immigration systems has led to a two-tiered system that system- atically disadvantages undocumented immigrants (Stumpf, 2006). Individuals of Mexican heritage who are within federal prisons for offenses related to immigration increased in the years 1994 to 2010 from 2,074 to 17,720 (U.S. Department of Justice, 2013). In fact, arrests for offenses related to immigra- tion (e.g., undocumented entry, smuggling others) currently surpass all other offense types and account for 50% of arrests by the federal government (Gramlich & Bialik, 2017). The disproportionate numbers of offenses related to immigration worsened in spring 2018 when the U.S. Attorney General and Homeland Security Secretary enacted a policy of arrest and apprehension of all persons seeking to enter the country illegally, including individuals pre- senting themselves to immigration officials seeking asylum (Moore, 2018; Varghese et al. 701 Pham, 2018). This policy also led to the separation of children from their parents at the border, although this portion of the Homeland Security policy was contested by the American Civil Liberties Union in the summer of 2018, with the courts ruling that families could not be separated, and separated families needed to be reunified (see Thompson, 2019). Regarding the former policy of separating families, whose effects are still being felt, it is important to explore the relationship between immigration and correctional detainment. In the next section, we discuss detention as it pertains to undocumented immigrants and unaccompanied minors. Pertinent history, demographics, and legislation. A basic historical understanding of immigration laws and trends is foundational to understanding the current state of government conditions relevant to undocumented immigrants. The U.S. Immigration and Nationality Action of 1965 represented a move from national immigration quotas toward a preference for immigrants who pre- sented with desired skills and family reunification. This act eliminated the discriminatory quota system by removing national origin, including ancestry, to deny immigration to the United States. However, the Act retained restric- tions about the number of immigrants who could come from different regions of the world, with more stringent restrictions placed on countries in the East- ern hemisphere. The Act also created a seven-category preference system still used today, and gives priority for immigration to relatives of U.S. citizens and legally permanent residents as well as to professionals and other individuals with specialized skills. However, the Act placed the first immigration cap on individuals from Latin American countries, including Mexico, which resulted in what many consider an unachievable naturalization process for Latin American immigrants (Ewing, 2012). In 2017, the Pew Research Center reported that 10.5 million undocu- mented immigrants were living in the United States (Krogstad, Passel, & Cohn, 2019). Data on the nationality of undocumented immigrants indi- cate that the majority were Latinx individuals (Krogstad et al., 2019). Therefore, we will primarily explore issues relevant to Latinx undocu- mented immigrants. The Illegal Immigration Reform and Immigrant Responsibility Act of 1996 increased the number of undocumented immigrants detained and expanded the types of crimes for which those who are not citizens could be deported. The Immigration and Customs Enforcement agency was developed after September 11, 2001, in the Department of Homeland Security to enforce the Act and oversee increased detention and deportation activities. Recent federal (e.g., section 287 [g] agreements of the Illegal Immigration Reform and Immigrant Resposibility Act) and state legislation (e.g., in Arizona, 702 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) California, Georgia) placed the enforcement of immigration policy in the hands of the local law enforcement (Hacker et al., 2011). Other state legisla- tion attempted to expand law enforcement personnel’s role in deportations. For example, California Proposition 187, which was later deemed unconsti- tutional and was overturned in federal court, required publicly funded health care facilities to not provide care but instead report to the government, any undocumented immigrants who sought care (Dwyer, 2004). This legislation contributed to xenophobia, an unwelcoming health care environment, and native-born citizens’ fears that trying to receive services may lead to deten- tion for undocumented family members (Hacker et al., 2011). Amidst the heightened xenophobic environment, recent federal immigrant programs such as the Criminal Alien Program and Secure Communities granted immi- gration officials authority to identify those who are not citizens in local jails and transfer them into federal immigration custody upon their release from jail (Chacón, 2012). This increased focus on detaining and deporting undocu- mented immigrants occurred despite research demonstrating that immigrants do not commit crimes at higher rates than those who are native-born (e.g., Chacón, 2012). Undocumented immigrant adults. On Thursday, June 7, 2018, it was announced that approximately 1,600 immigration detainees would be sent to federal prisons, marking the first time federal prisons would be used for such a large number of immigrants (Lynch & Cook, 2018). The policy to arrest and detain undocumented immigrants expanded the need for more prisons. The increase in “crimmigration” (Stumpf, 2006) policies over the last decade has significantly extended the jail stays of undocumented immigrants in loca- tions where Immigration and Customs Enforcement detainers are honored. Specifically, local law enforcement agencies increasingly comply with requests by Immigration and Customs Enforcement that ask for information about a person who is about to be released from custody, or ask that the local agency hold the detained person for a longer period of time to facilitate that person’s deportation, regardless of whether the undocumented immigrant has any criminal charges or convictions (Beckett & Evans, 2015). Addition- ally, these programs also led to a higher number of Latinx being detained, most of whom had not been convicted of serious crimes, had no prior crimi- nal records, and did “not pose serious security risks to the community” (Beckett & Evans, 2015, p. 253). Research suggests that undocumented immigrants are more likely to be incarcerated with longer sentences than citizens (see Iles & Adegun, 2018). Immigrants also experience negative stereotypes and stigmatization, which may further exacerbate unjust prac- tices in the justice system (APA, 2012). Varghese et al. 703 Undocumented, unaccompanied immigrant minors (UUIM). Between October 1, 2015, and August 31, 2016, the U.S. Customs and Border Patrol apprehended nearly 55,000 undocumented, unaccompanied immigrant minors at the bor- der of the southwest region of the United States (U.S. Customs and Border Protection, 2016). UUIM cross the border into the United States to afford themselves and their families a better future (Aldarondo & Becker, 2011; Becker Herbst et al., 2018). UUIM have reported taking a perilous journeys characterized by extreme hunger and thirst, physical injuries, illness, risk of physical harm, and poor treatment from immigration officials (Becker Herbst et al., 2018). Youth who enter the U.S. immigration system are held in cus- tody by the subsidiary agencies of the U.S. Department of Homeland Secu- rity. In addition, within the Immigration and Customs Enforcement agency, Enforcement and Removal Operations can apprehend youth who have not entered the system but are suspected of violating immigration law. Through either pathway, the youth is placed in the custody of the Department of Homeland Security. As a next step, most UUIM are transferred to the Office of Refugee Resettlement and placed into detention facilities to await their immigration process outcome (Menjívar & Perreira, 2019). While waiting, many youth are placed in short-term holding cells called las hieleras [the freezers] for up to two weeks (Becker Herbst et al., 2018; Jones & Podkul, 2012). These facilities may be so overcrowded that youth have to take turns lying down on the concrete floor. Most youth report having inadequate food and water, enduring frigid temperatures, and lacking access to bathing facilities. Many youth report experiencing excessive physical force, having belongings taken away, and being subjected to racial slurs (Jones & Podkul, 2012). Particularly vulnerable youth (e.g., under 13 years of age) are typically placed in foster care (Menjívar & Perreira, 2019). The remaining youth are placed across the country in shelters that are given the responisibility to com- ply with federal law in the care and supervision of immigrant children (National Immigrant Justice Center, 2013). Secure care shelters are used for youth with violent offenses or those who are a threat to self or others. Staff- secure care shelters are used for children with a history of nonviolent crimes or those who pose a risk to run away. Youth with no prior criminal justice involvement are placed in detention shelters, the least restrictive environment. Detention may last one day to over two years, but typically lasts two months (Byrne & Miller, 2012). Approximately 65% of youth within the Office of Refugee Resettlement are reunified with a sponsor, often a parent in the United States. When a parental sponsor is not possible, youth are released to a legal guardian, adult relative, or another approved individual. Youth may try to seek asylum, receive special immigrant juvenile status under visas for abused youth 704 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) or victims of human trafficking, or voluntarily repatriate themselves (Byrne & Miller, 2012). Physical and Mental Health Consequences of Incarceration and Detention For at least some people, physical and mental health might be neglected once detained (Wilper et al., 2009). An analysis of national data of inmates in jails as well as state and federal prisons found that over 30% of those in prisons and over half of those in jails had not taken medication for mental health conditions upon incarceration (Wilper et al., 2009). For those with physical health symp- toms, over 20% of those in prison and over 35% of those in jails stopped taking medications for physical symptoms upon incarceration; after a serious physical injury, 7.7% of federal prisoners, 12% of state prisoners, and 24.7% of jail detainees did not see medical staff (Wilper et al., 2009). People who are incar- cerated are much more likely to be at risk of suicide than the general population (see Fazel, Hayes, Bartellas, Clerici, & Trustman, 2016). Prisons can be especially dangerous for vulnerable populations. For exam- ple, juveniles sentenced as adults and sent to adult facilities are at higher risk for sexual assault by an adult prisoner than those not sentenced to adult pris- ons (National Prison Rape Elimination Commission Report, 2009). Transgender individuals face higher rates of abuse in prison than their cisgen- der peers, and transgender People of Color report higher levels of abuse than their White counterparts; those incarcerated also had worse health than those who had not been incarcerated (Reisner et al., 2014). A systematic review of the influence of immigration policies on the status of undocumented immigrants found that these policies were associated with lower access to health services and an increase in depression and anxiety (Gonzales, Suárez-Orozco, & Dedios-Sanguineti, 2013). Legislative and pro- cedural changes related to undocumented immigrants may be associated with undocumented immigrants’ increased risk of violence in their homes and communities, as they are less likely to seek police protection when experi- encing domestic and community violence (APA, 2012; Menjívar, 2006). UUIM especially lack resources to ameliorate these stressors, given that seeking social support within the cultural community can be difficult as it may risk disclosing immigration status (Gonzales et al., 2013). From the literature provided thus far, it is clear that there is injustice in the justice system, particularly for People of Color. An unjust system, however, does not mean that those working within the system are unjust or unwilling to change. Further, given that some laws and policies may not have been developed primarily with racist intent (e.g., Stand Your Ground laws), at least Varghese et al. 705 some of the injustice may be the result of a lack of awareness that actions may be leading to divergent outcomes for People of Color. Justice reform is supported by a diverse array of people, including individuals who are racially diverse and from diverse political backgrounds. This can be seen by the pass- ing of the First Step Act of 2018 (Public Law No. 115-391) under the Trump Administration, which received bipartisan support and is an important step in justice reform. Therefore, in the next section we encourage counseling psy- chologists to work toward justice reform, including partnering with various justice system entities. Counseling Psychology Framework for Justice System Advocacy As mentioned previously in this document and illustrated in Table 1, counsel- ing psychologists are well-positioned to tackle the challenges of justice reform. Equipped with the knowledge and skills of the field, including research, advocacy, and the ability to teach, counseling psychologists can be part of generating knowledge, developing policy, and training others. This section describes practical ways counseling psychologists can help reform the justice system and describes some of the challenges as well. Generate Knowledge Counseling psychologists’ training in research methods and data analysis enables them to conduct robust research relevant to promoting justice in the justice system. Such research includes the root causes of offending behavior, ways to reduce biases in the justice system, strategies to enhance protective factors, and evidence-based methods to decrease societal problems associ- ated with justice system involvement. This section covers several potential research areas and challenges. Policy-relevant research. Research can form a basis for policy by studying the societal issues that policies are intended to address, as well as by investigating the assumptions underlying policy decisions. To enhance impact, counseling psychologists can conduct research with clearly delineated implications for policy. Relatedly, research can help fill the knowledge gaps about how to reduce bias in the courts. For example, a quasi-experimental study involving the death penalty found that providing simple juror instructions and ensuring that the jurors were a racially diverse group resulted in less bias against Black defendants (Shaked-Schroer, Costanzo, & Marcus-Newhall, 2008). Research can also bolster advocacy efforts by expanding the evidence base for humane 706 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) policies. For example, preliminary research supports the benefits of alternative courts, such as mental health and drug courts, for People of Color. Access to such courts could promote treatment, which may be more beneficial rather than default sentencing such as detainment (Subramanian, Riley, & Mai, 2018). Evaluation of interventions, policies, and practices. Counseling psychologists can apply research skills to evaluate implementation of policies and prac- tices within the justice system. Research and evaluations by counseling psy- chologists could assess the effectiveness of programming as an empirical question. This could encourage the development of alternatives to detention that advance public safety and reduce recidivism. For example, research using a randomized design to evaluate the effectiveness of correctional pro- grams could elucidate which correctional programs work better than others and why. Given the lack of attention to culturally responsive programming (Bonta & Andrews, 2017), questions could focus on the development of culturally competent correctional programs. Counseling psychologists could also test the effectiveness of existing culture-specific programs in order to strengthen them and expeand their implementation. A starting place for this research may be the creation of partnerships between counseling psycholo- gists and correctional agencies, with an emphasis on analyzing existing data to evaluate the effectiveness of current programming for People of Color. Further, restorative justice programs are gaining more attention, but there is not enough evidence of their effectiveness. Thus, research in this area is also warranted. Investigate experiences of those affected by injustice. Counseling psycholo- gists’ competence in research methods associated with empowerment, such as community-based participatory research, aligns directly with these aims. Furthermore, extant counseling psychology research can provide insight into how sociopolitical forces influence the physical and mental health of oppressed groups. Given CRT’s emphasis on understanding perspectives of People of Color, qualitative research that explores the phenomenological experiences of People of Color can contribute meaningfully to justice reform. Counseling psychology research could help fill gaps in understanding the unique experi- ences of individuals in the justice system, such as the unique pathways of Girls of Color who interact with this system (Krisberg, 2018). Research may also focus on school personnel’s interactions with at-risk youth, with the aim of preventing juvenile justice system involvement. Counseling psychologists can provide valuable expertise to schools and form research partnerships that can be a fruitful way to combat structural issues for Varghese et al. 707 youth at risk of justice involvement. For example, partnerships between researchers and schools may address one of these structural issues, school dropout. In this effort, goals might include (a) identification of reasons stu- dents are not graduating (Jacobson, 2018), and (b) data collection with the aim of developing a program focused on academic success (University of Central Arkansas, 2018). Research has shown that school engagement, atten- dance (Blomberg, Bales, & Piquero, 2012; Li & Lerner, 2011), and academic success (Hoffman, Erickson, & Spence, 2013) are associated with less delin- quent behavior. Consistent with CRT’s approach to understanding the unique narratives of People of Color, qualitative research that allows for the phenomenological understanding of the experiences of transgender Women of Color who have been incarcerated can provide valuable insight into the development of poli- cies relevant to making correctional facilities safer for this population. Through accurate understanding of offending behavior from the perspective of offenders, policy makers and providers can more effectively implement systemic changes. As stipulated by the APA’s Multicultural guidelines: An ecological approach to context, identity, and intersectionality (2017), psy- chologists are to take a “strength-based approach when working with . . . groups, communities and organizations that seek to build resilience and decrease trauma within the sociocultural context” (p. 188). Study Public Perceptions and Attitudes That Perpetuate Injustice Counseling psychology expertise regarding measurement of explicit and implicit attitudes can be useful in gathering information regarding public per- ceptions of law enforcement and of people who are disproportionately disad- vantaged in the justice system. The National Institute of Justice (Klockars, Ivkovich, Harver, & Haberfeld, 2000) released a report on the blue code of silence, or the reluctance of police officers to report misconduct of fellow officers, and revealed that most police officers would not report less serious cases, but were more likely to report more serious cases. One way to reduce such codes of silence is to mandate agencies to report (Rothwell & Baldwin, 2007). Investigating police perceptions and attitudes toward the public may be one way to identify areas of potential bias that would benefit from inter- vention. In addition to quantitative research, public perception surveys require varied research methods and paradigms to avoid reinforcing the sta- tus quo. For example, studying police perceptions of Black community mem- bers may require an ethnographic approach to reduce participants’ tendency to respond in a socially desirable manner. Observing behavior in the field 708 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) allows for the triangulation of data. Furthermore, the examination of how racially marginalized community members perceive police presence in their neighborhoods may require a critical research paradigm to represent the unspoken power dynamics inherent in police–community interactions. Another approach to studying perceptions aligns with the strengths-based value of counseling psychology. Research that invites community members to describe an ideal relationship between law enforcement and their commu- nity rightly assumes that members of marginalized communities offer a cru- cial perspective upon which to evaluate policies and practices that may be most effective. These findings can be used to draft recommendations for local law enforcement agencies. Generating Knowledge: Challenges and Strategies There are numerous challenges counseling psychologists may encounter when conducting research and evaluation related to the justice system. First, many counseling psychologists may not have considered ways in which their research interests and skills are relevant to the justice system. Ideally, the ideas presented in this article may help develop or apply a research program to address relevant questions and concerns. A significant strength is that counseling psychologists are trained in a variety of research designs and ana- lytical procedures that are quite relevant to answer questions involving the justice system; therefore, preparation of counseling psychologists in commu- nity-based participatory research, qualitative research, program evaluation, survey research, and experimental design are all relevant. Considering the needs of the community and developing research questions that can intersect with our individual research programs, may be fruitful to the community, advance our research, and promote systemic change—a powerful combina- tion. Beyond the commitment and skills to conduct research relevant to the justice system, funding may be needed to carry out these studies. Fortunately, there are funding agencies that support this research, such as the National Institute of Justice. One considerable research challenge is to access the systems, individuals, and communities of interest. Gaining inroads in law enforcement agencies to conduct research that may represent these agencies in an accurate, but perhaps unfavorable, light is difficult. Establishing relationships that are mutually ben- eficial, such as being willing to provide a service (e.g., training) for law enforce- ment officers in exchange for access, may be one way to open the door for ethical, critical research. Finally, marginalized communities are often the focus of research studies in a way that does not honor their worldviews or provide any benefits. Similar to the recommendation for relationship building with law Varghese et al. 709 enforcement, establishing ongoing connections with marginalized communi- ties and providing valuable services (e.g., outreach, consultation, advocacy) to them may be one way to enhance recruitment for public perceptions research. Interpret and Disseminate Knowledge Counseling psychologists are well-positioned to interpret research and to dis- seminate knowledge gained through systematic inquiry. They may use their competence in education and training to influence the justice system infra- structure through a number of mechanisms, described next. Share knowledge with policy makers and courts. Counseling psychologists can share knowledge through various mechanisms, including lobbying and writ- ing or supporting amicus briefs. Central to CRT, counseling psychologists can directly engage with the public and policy makers by educating them about institutional racism and bias within the laws and courts, by training justice system personnel to prevent and reduce the use of force, and by pro- moting cultural competence. Counseling psychologists may also engage in advocacy through formal networks such as the Society of Counseling Psy- chology and APA, focusing on effective collaborative efforts to change laws and policies. As noted, the United States has enacted a policy of separating children from their families in the name of “deterrence” at border crossings (U.S. Department of State, 2018). In response, numerous organizations, including the Society of Counseling Psychology, joined together in the devel- opment of an additional statement that further underscored the pernicious health effects of this policy on children and families (“Joint Public Statement by Psychology Groups on U.S. Immigration Policies and Practices”, 2018). Such collaborative efforts may contribute to policy change. Considering the effectiveness of multisystemic interventions in prevent- ing and reducing juvenile justice involvement (see Bartol & Bartol, 2017), transforming oppressive systems in schools and neighborhoods is critical, as is advocating for more financial, educational, and health care resources that enable parents to promote the well-being of children and families. For exam- ple, counseling psychologists can advocate for policies that provide vouchers for families in impoverished and unsafe neighborhoods, such as neighbor- hoods with structural issues such as lead exposure, to connect families with better housing (Robinson et al., 2015). Such transformations would allow for greater contextual supports, including prosocial peer groups, which can serve as a protective factor against juvenile justice involvement for boys and girls (Bartol & Bartol, 2017; Bonta & Andrews, 2017). 710 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) Counseling psychologists can work at state and federal levels to promote policies that ameliorate disparities in detention and incarceration. One inno- vative policy in the state of Iowa requires “Minority Impact Statements” (Bonnie et al., 2013) of every organization that applies for a state grant, and requires applicants to enact various safeguards to prevent bias and discrimi- nation. Specifically, the state requires a discussion of (a) how the program will disproportionately influence minorities; (b) reasons for why this dispro- portionate impact is necessary; and (c) “evidence of consultation of represen- tatives of minority persons in cases where a policy or program has an identifiable impact on minority persons in this state” (“Grant Applications — Minority Impact Statements,” 2018, p.1). Finally, given that community-based interventions are the most effective in reducing recidivism according to best practices in corrections (Bonta & Andrews, 2017), counseling psychologists can also play a key role in advo- cating for laws and policies that employ community-based methods of reha- bilitation that reduce recidivism. At the juvenile level, such policies resulted in detention center closures, including the reduction of Latinx populations detained in juvenile detention centers (Bonnie et al., 2013). Policies advocat- ing for community-based programs may focus on specific subpopulations, such as youth who would benefit from additional mental health care or basic resources instead of placement in a juvenile detention center (Bonnie et al., 2013). For example, Conneticut passed a law in 2007 to stop detention for status offenders (e.g., runaways) and instead provide them with alternative treatments; the law also prohibits individuals younger than 18 to be tried as adults (Tow Youth Justice Institute, 2017). These reforms have led to decreases in recidivism (Tow Youth Justice Institute, 2017). Counseling psy- chologists can join advisory committees and state and local task forces to provide guidance in matters such as these. Professional Development and Consultation with Justice System Employees Counseling psychologists can disseminate accurate information, counteract psychological barriers to justice, and cultivate skills among justice system employees. Those who work in or with the justice system may benefit from increased knowledge about bias. Counseling psychologists with requisite expertise could provide training to judges, jurors, and attorneys, on relevant topics such as the nature of implicit bias, ways to overcome implicit bias, and ways to optimize fairness in jury decision-making. Given the often uncon- scious nature of bias, efforts to counteract biases that may affect sentencing Varghese et al. 711 are warranted. Some possible solutions include auditing of court decisions, teaching mindfulness meditation to court personnel, and providing evidence that does not agree with preconceived notions (Wistrich & Rachlinski, 2017). Also, given the aforementioned findings of bias (Levinson et al., 2017), judges might consider how they might sentence a person if that person were from a different background (Wistrich & Rachlinski, 2017). For example, when sentencing a Black male defendant, judges might consider how the sentence might differ if the defendant were White. This may be important for both White and non-White judges, as racism can be directed toward other groups or internalized toward one’s own group (David, 2013). To the extent that the life circumstances of those being sentenced differ from the judges’ experiences, such perspective taking could reduce bias experienced by mar- ginalized communities. These efforts would dovetail with counseling psy- chologists’ competence in cultural issues, including their expertise in the development of self-awareness of biases, and knowledge and skills in work- ing with diverse populations. Diversity training for law enforcement. Because disproportionate use of force and other biased behaviors tend to be directed against certain minority popu- lations (e.g., Swaine & McCarthy, 2017), an important mechanism for improving the justice system is the preparation of law enforcement personnel to interact fairly with marginalized people. Promising work in the arenas of implicit bias and fair and impartial policing advance efforts to curb law enforcement personnel’s role in escalation of conflict and use of deadly force (Fridell, 2017). Diversity training for law enforcement personnel has often focused on the development of concrete behaviors such as intercultural com- munication (e.g., Cornett-DeVito & McGlone, 2000) and affirming tactics (e.g., Israel et al., 2016). Intercultural communication includes skills when working with diverse populations, including expression of empathy and the ability to adapt to others’ needs (Cornett-DeVito & McGLone, 2000). Across the varied training content, trainers must understand and attend to the context of law enforcement personnel’s experiences, concerns, and organizational culture, as well as account for local and national attention on law enforce- ment personnel’s treatment of marginalized individuals. Law enforcement officers may further benefit by understanding interac- tions with marginalized communities in the context of historical and societal oppression. They need to earn trust and respect from Communities of Color, appreciating that the historical role of law enforcement in upholding laws has been used to enforce enslavement, Jim Crow laws, internment, and anti- immigration agendas. Even Officers of Color may still be viewed suspi- ciously in their work, although some research suggests diverse police forces are less likely to use deadly force (McElvain & Kposowa, 2008). 712 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) CRT and theories of internalized racism (Jones, 2000) suggest people across all racial backgrounds are socialized to view People of Color as having less worth and power than Whites. Thus, officers trained to enforce policies that enact paternalistic surveillance of People of Color may even subcon- sciously perceive Whites as less likely to commit crimes and more likely to have the power to successfully hold People of Color accountable. Therefore, specific training that requires officers to discuss and process prejudiced mes- sages and stereotypes can make visible biased assumptions, and enable offi- cers to replace them. These stereotypes could be replaced with messages about community strengths, thus making it less likely for officers to act more violently toward People of Color (James, Fridell, & Straub, 2016). Law enforcement officers will become engaged through the provision of training that they perceive as relevant and effective (Coderoni, 2002). Recommended approaches for diversity training include the use of simula- tions, group exercises and problem solving scenarios, case studies, and mini- lectures; and the provision of job-relevant information (Birzer, 1999; Cornett-DeVito & McGlone, 2000). It may be particularly effective to have officers serve as trainers using a team-teach approach, with trainers repre- senting different organizations (Hennessy, 2001). Rich opportunities exist for counseling psychologists to partner with the courts for training. Counseling psychologists can train those who work in corrections on strategies to decrease bias in assessment and placement. For example, parole and probation officers can be taught that some assessment questions can be culturally biased and that not adhering to some majority cultural norms does not necessarily indicate deviance. Helping parole and probation officers develop cultural competence skills may enhance rapport with juveniles in corrections and lead to better outcomes. For example, a study of 109 people on parole found that parolees who viewed their parole officers as caring and trustworthy were less likely to be rearrested (Kennealy, Skeem, Manchak, & Louden, 2012). Empower Communities With Knowledge Advocacy for justice system reform can occur at various levels and at differ- ent points in the process. In the same way that legal clinics in law schools offer pro bono representation and trial preparation, counseling psychology graduate training clinics can offer counseling and preparation for managing the challenges of dealing with members of disenfranchised groups in the criminal justice system. Advocacy can occur through partnerships with local NGOs and local government as well as with affiliations with local offices of national organizations. For example, the Immigrant Children and Legal Services Partnership in South Florida, an organization with which counseling Varghese et al. 713 psychology faculty and students have partnered, employs “an integrated, child-centered model of expert legal counsel and advocacy, trauma-oriented mental health services, resilience-building youth development programming, and professional development of staff caring for UUIMs in local detention facilities” (Aldarondo & Becker, 2011, p. 2010). Counseling psychologists could advocate for each of those dimensions. The more diverse the coalition representing multiple constituents, the greater the credibility to support the change (“Community Toolbox: Learning a Skill”, 2018). Challenges for counseling psychologists will be to influence outcomes through advocacy based on empirical support and on implementing professional values, with- out taking on a deliberately partisan approach. For People of Color with a criminal background, obtaining job qualifica- tions could reduce some employment barriers (e.g., Varghese, Hardin, & Bauer, 2009). Davis et al. (2013) of the RAND Corporation found that par- ticipation in prison education programs decreased probability of recidivating by 43%. Access to a college education can further increase job acquisition, but one barrier to college education is a 1994 federal law that denies people who are incarcerated from receiving Pell Grants (Olivas & Jones, 2017). Counseling psychologists could advocate for reinstating access to Pell Grants and other sources of educational funding for those who are imprisoned. After release, this education can allow these same individuals to give back to their communities in various ways, including their payment of taxes as a result of employment. Inform the Public Counseling psychologists are uniquely prepared to engage in leadership roles given their training in understanding human behavior, ability to work with diverse populations, and competence to listen and build rapport. Serving in these capacities can situate counseling psychologists in a position where they can serve as a potent force toward transforming unjust laws and policies (Varghese et al., 2017). Nationally, counseling psychologists could provide leadership in diverse settings, such as holding positions in public policy orga- nizations focused on changing unjust policies. Counseling psychologists could contribute to these entities by harnessing their training in research with diverse and marginalized communities, their ability to critically evaluate information, and their social-justice focus to inform public policy and influ- ence national discourse. For example, counseling psychologists can influence the conversation surrounding immigration policy by providing the public accurate information about Latinx immigration, thereby dispelling xenopho- bic assumptions and stereotypes (see APA, 2012). Specifically, psychologists 714 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) could provide evidence that undocumented immigrants of Latinx origin often immigrate to the United States to flee violence, obtain an education, become financially stable, and support others (Aldarondo & Becker, 2011). Such ini- tiatives can provide evidence to promote an authentic understanding of the immigrant experience and promote empathy. Counseling psychologists could also use their voice to inform the public regarding the connection between macrolevel and microlevel implications of inequitable treatment (Toporek & Daniels, 2018). For example, commercial sexual exploitation is inextricably linked to issues of social injustice (APA, 2014). The detrimental impact of structural inequality must be acknowledged in order to gain a deeper and more accurate understanding of commercial sexual exploitation. Counseling psychologists can aid policy makers and pro- viders in more effectively responding to the needs of CSEC by attending to systemic power dynamics that further disenfranchise vulnerable youth. Such exposure may demonstrate that dehumanizing methods (e.g., treating victim- ized youth as delinquent) run counter to the espoused U.S. values of justice, equity, and human rights. Interpreting and Disseminating Knowledge: Challenges and Strategies Counseling psychologists may lack the time, resources, or knowledge to effectively disseminate policy-relevant research. Whereas counseling psy- chologists may be familiar with preparation of research findings for profes- sional journals and conference presentations, they may be less equipped to write white papers, craft op-ed articles, collaborate with community mem- bers, and provide training for nonpsychologists. Advocacy training can help counseling psychologists increase their effec- tiveness in sharing knowledge with policy makers. A focus on competencies related to therapy may limit training programs’ inclusion of didactic and experiential training on advocacy and the legal system, as the latter is not a requirement of profession-wide competency in the APA Standards of Accreditation (APA Commission on Accreditation, 2018). Doctoral programs may work to incorporate these topics into their coursework or practica; how- ever, it requires effort to structure and sequence advocacy within required competencies as outlined by the Standards of Accreditation. To address these gaps, the APA’s Legislative Issues and Advocacy Training Tools website pro- vides resources on effective advocacy strategies with webinars and training modules (APA, 2018b). Further, the Society of Counseling Psychology, Society for Community Research and Action, Society for the Psychology of Women, and Society for the Psychological Study of Culture, Ethnicity and Varghese et al. 715 Race collaborated to create an additional training tool kit titled Community Advocacy: Training Psychologists to Act Locally that presents different strat- egies to change policy at various levels of government (APA, 2018a). Another challenge to effectively engaging in advocacy is the capacity to devote sufficient time and energy to be an effective advocate, while balanc- ing other professional roles. It takes time and effort to develop trusting rela- tionships with community members and inform the public, and patience to see the results. Finally, a challenge is that the effectiveness of training can be limited. According to the Federal Judicial Center, research has shown that implicit bias training has helped reduce implicit preferences a person has toward a particular group, particularly preference for Whites over Blacks (Federal Judicial Center, 2019). However, they report that the effects of the training may last for just a couple of weeks, and may not be long-term. This indicates that training may need to be continuous and not simply a one-time event. Take Action Based on Evidence, Skills, and Values Policy-making. Counseling psychologists can play a role in influencing public policy. Participating in APA Congressional Fellowships or other national fel- lowships can enable counseling psychologists to engage in policy-making. Further, counseling psychologists can run for various local, state, and national offices. Psychologists who previously worked in academia have been elected to the U.S. House of Representatives (e.g., Alan Lowenthal, Judy Chu), and psychologists with law degrees have served as judges (e.g., Michael O. Miller; see Skaggs, 2019). Even nonelected positions can help make policy. Among the most coura- geous acts of leadership are nonviolent protests and civil disobedience to unjust laws, often leading to changes in these laws. Such leadership has been the mark of transformational leaders such as Gandhi and Martin Luther King, Jr., who, even in the face of brutal injustice, led nonviolent protests by refusing to comply with unjust laws. Counseling psychologists’ core values of social justice and diversity allow for such a transformational leadership style (Varghese et al., 2017), particularly in light of immoral, unjust, and unconscio- nable laws and policies. Today, nonviolent resistance might occur in the form of outreach to undocumented individuals and the provision of mental health care or sanctuary (Fournier, 2018). Modern examples of civil disobedience include German pilots who refused to deport asylum seekers (Fournier, 2018) and the action of former Attorney General Sally Yates who refused to support the travel ban against individuals from Muslim countries, detailing this ban’s violation of the U.S. Department of Justice’s values (Chakraborly, 2018). 716 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) Protests of psychologists’ participation in torture reflects leadership of coun- seling psychologists in taking a stand for their principles by questioning authority and refusing to compromise with policies that conflict with profes- sional values regardless of possible deleterious consequences. Advance Implementation of Evidence-Based Practice Consultation. The training of counseling psychologists includes preparation for serving as consultants to legal and legislative systems, governmental entities, and human service organizations. In these consulting roles, counseling psy- chologists can advance development and implementation of evidence-based programs to reduce disparities. Therefore, to promote procedural and distribu- tive justice, counseling psychologists can partner with social entities such as schools, probation and parole agencies, judges, juvenile detention centers, and immigration detention centers, to make changes within these agencies. Counseling psychologists can support school staff in disrupting the school- to-prison pipeline. For example, one university partnership between a doc- toral program in school psychology and a school district is focused on prevention and intervention, such that middle school students have a greater likelihood of positive outcomes in academics, behavior, and social and emo- tional development (University of Central Arkansas, 2018)—factors associ- ated with lower delinquent behavior (Li & Lerner, 2011). Such partnerships may address risk factors by helping staff engage in positive strategies to change behavior, provide an emotional regulation curriculum, and create a supportive and trusting environment that mitigates individual and societal risk (Bonta & Andrews, 2017). Counseling psychologists can advocate for appropriate programs for People of Color, including women and girls, as well as transgender youth and adults. This includes ending the detention of girls who run away (Krisberg, 2018) and advocating for the provision of alternative interventions relevant to gender. Detention centers, prisons, and U.S. community corrections need to improve their treatment of minority populations (National Center for Transgender Equality, 2018). For example, policies continue to be erratic towards gender minorities, with the current policy now indicating that bio- logical sex will be used to initially determine where the transgender person will be assigned (U.S. DOJ Federal Bureau of Prisons, 2018). Although U.S. DOJ Federal Bureau of Prisons (2018) has indicated that it will work to miti- gate risks, the transgender community had noted that this will increase the risk of sexual assault of transgender persons in prison (National Center for Transgender Equality, 2018). Further, racial minorities with some of the low- est academic and work achievements appear to be some of the least likely to Varghese et al. 717 obtain training and work experience in prisons (Rampey et al., 2016). Finally, in a study using surveys and interviews with 65 professionals and staff in the juvenile system, 63% reported that they were not aware of diversion pro- grams culturally competent to LGBT youth (Majd, Marksamer, & Reyes, 2009). Yet, programming tailored to the needs of diverse groups can be help- ful in rehabilitative efforts. For example, culturally competent interventions for the indigenous Maori of New Zealand, such as involving family and Maori cultural values, are used in reentry efforts (Richards-Ward & McDaniel, 2007). Such interventions are in line with correctional best-practice princi- ples of responsivity to individual differences (Bonta & Andrews, 2017). Evidence-based practice. Counseling psychologists can advocate for courts to implement evidence-based practices, such as effectively conducting risk assessments to place youth in appropriate settings. This would be important to ensure that high-risk youth receive the most intensive services, such as detention, but low risk youth do not receive such intensive services, which might be harmful to them (Bonta & Andrews, 2017). Arkansas requires all juvenile courts to use risk assessments in order to place only those youth who are at high risk in a detention center, consistent with evidence-based practices that include reducing detention of low-risk youth (Arkansas Act 189, 2019). One juvenile court judge noted that a court partnership with universities cre- ated alternative programs instead of detention for lower risk youth (KATV News, 2017). Further, counseling psychologists could work with the courts to encourage partnerships with schools to provide mediation for troubled Youth of Color. For example, juvenile courts in one county partnered with a school district to have a mediator intervene in discipline cases in schools, to ensure that poor behavioral issues do not escalate toward arrest and court referrals (personal communication, Attorney Chastity Scifres, October 12, 2018). Crisis intervention teams are another practice for which counseling psy- chologists can advocate and help implement. In several recent high-profile killings of People of Color by police and jail personnel, the victims had a mental health diagnosis. Crisis intervention is specifically designated as a critical training need, and mental health response training is often mandated (The President’s Task Force on 21st Century Policing, 2015). The Memphis model of crisis intervention team (CIT) training is perhaps the most success- ful use of psychologists and other mental health workers in law enforcement officer’s training (Compton, Bahora, Watson, & Oliva, 2008, Heilbrun et al., 2012). In the 40-hour training sequences for CIT, officers partner with local mental health and substance abuse treatment personnel in the local commu- nity to simulate situations in which officers respond to a call when a mental health crisis is occurring. 718 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) Counseling psychologists may identify and advocate for effective ways to address trauma experienced by law enforcement personnel. Police officers suffer from accumulated on-the-job traumatic stress and may develop classic symptoms of PTSD and depression. One study of police officers found that 16% of officers had depression, but the prevalence of PTSD was over 30% (Darensburg et al., 2006). Psychologists have worked closely with law enforcement agencies to provide officers with health-promoting activities such as wellness programs and critical incident debriefing (Chism, 2016). There are some systemic mechanisms that can support counseling psy- chologists’ efforts to advocate for evidence-based practices. One such tool is consent agreements. Almost all the consent decrees (i.e., agreements in the last 10 years between the U.S. DOJ and a local city or district to reform and monitor a law enforcement agency) under the oversight of the federal court have included provisions for robust increases in the training and oversight of training for police officers (e.g., U.S. v. Cleveland, 2015). Some agreements specifically require law enforcement personnel to implement policies, train- ing, and accountability systems related to use of force, deescalation tech- niques, and strategies for working with individuals with a disability (e.g., U.S. v. Cleveland, 2015). Many of these provisions contain specific language for the inclusion of psychologists in the design, instruction, and oversight of new recruit training, as well as in-service training at least at the patrol-officer level. The consent agreements offer opportunities to become involved in community oversight of police agencies, but they have stirred up resentment among police union officials who claim that this will hinder their ability to do their job (Miletech, 2019). CRT anticipates this and warns against becoming involved while not attending to the efforts to resist accountability. Counseling psychology’s attention to strengths-based approaches can help to advocate for law enforcement personnel’s training in diversity issues, given potential resistance from officers. Law enforcement personnel may be resistant to diversity training if they perceive this training is a consequence of wrongdoing; however, acknowledging existing culturally informed policies and tactics, while acknowledging what they are already doing well, may help officers be more open to advancing their understanding of marginalized groups (Israel et al., 2017). Targeted Community Prevention and Intervention Community collaboration. Counseling psychologists can promote distribu- tive and procedural justice in equitable treatment by law enforcement per- sonnel by establishing long-term partnerships with communities that are under high surveillance and overrepresented in negative police encounters. Varghese et al. 719 Connecting with places of worship, community organizations, and disen- franchised community members, positions law enforcement officers to dismantle stereotypical biases through positive engagement. Additionally, counseling psychologists are well-suited to facilitate the process of recruit- ing community members to participate in training police academy mem- bers, staff and trainees, to provide community-aware, culturally relevant strategies for systemic change. Counseling psychologists can utilize their skills to develop effective inter- ventions to reduce and prevent behaviors that lead to the imposition of fines and fees. Such interventions might include processes to support individuals’ successful compliance with sentencing (e.g., sending postcards with remind- ers about court dates to prevent the accrual of further fines; see Council of Economic Advisors Brief, 2015). This category of preventive public health approaches and initiatives to reduce recidivism can comprise another element of a research agenda. Community trauma. Just as law enforcement officers experience trauma, mar- ginalized communities who interact with them also experience trauma. Sys- temic heterosexism, ethnocentrism, and racism intersect with the traumas imposed on marginalized communities from law enforcement. These trau- matic experiences result in race-based stress (Carter, 2007), minority stress (Meyer, 2003), or other identity-specific distress. Over time, a lack of com- bined systemic and individual intervention can lead to accumulated race- based stress (Clark, Anderson, Clark, & Williams, 1999) or racial trauma. Counseling psychologists can work in partnership with communities to address the impact of trauma, as well as to work collaboratively with law enforcement personnel to understand how community trauma may affect people’s perceptions of, and interactions with, law enforcement personnel. Across the United States, communities are developing community crisis response teams modeled on the National Organization for Victim Assis- tance’s (NOVA) Community Crisis Response training (NOVA, 2018). Mem- bers of the team are a diverse group of community volunteers who commit to responding to crises in their wider community (NOVA, 2018). Most major cities have some form of crisis response team that serves to provide healing to communities after a disaster. Crisis Response Teams often meet with orga- nizations such as the Red Cross and the families that have been affected by the crisis. Currently, such teams are not standardized across communities and some argue for more standardization. After the recent shooting of a homeless man by the Los Angeles Police Department, psychologist Vickie Mays was one of the Los Angeles Mayor’s crisis team members to respond (personal communication, August 2018). 720 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) Hargons et al. (2017) detailed strategies used by some counseling psy- chologists for actively intervening in various marginalized communities at the systemic, institutional, interpersonal, and individual levels. For example, after the shooting of Michael Brown in Ferguson, Missouri, counseling psy- chologist Jameca Falconer provided crisis intervention to community mem- bers experiencing distress (Hargons et al., 2017). The authors made additional recommendations about ways that counseling psychologists may seek to get involved. An important component of better mental health and behavioral outcomes is the ability to be a contributing member of society. Counseling psychologists could assist those on probation or parole find meaningful com- munity service activities to fulfill probation requirements and to develop pro- social attitudes. Helping the community can be difficult if one is not a member of the com- munity and is seen as an outsider. Communities need to trust the person pro- posing to help. Consequently, it is important for counseling psychologists to establish their credibility within a community. Their planning for such work must include preparation time as well as relationship-building activities such as pro bono efforts and community preparedness activities. This requires developing relationships and time. Counseling psychologists who are inter- ested in this work must be prepared to invest the substantial time and effort necessary to do it effectively. Further, helping communities heal from trauma is not easy work, and if counseling psychologists do not practice self-care, compassion fatigue and burnout can result. Self-care is essential. Some of these barriers can be overcome by working with a team of collaborators and partners and not letting the work consume a person. A primary tenet in crisis response is that it is work that cannot be reasonably undertaken alone. Developing an effective relationship with other crisis team members, perhaps even other psychologists, may be crucial to managing these requirements. Universal Prevention and Intervention Counseling psychologists can advocate for programs to help diverse popula- tions cope with adversity and flourish in difficult circumstances. Community factors such as violence, poverty, lack of support in school, and neglect can contribute to the likelihood of interacting with the justice system (Bartol & Bartol, 2017; Bonnie, Johnson, Chemers, & Schuck, 2013; Krivo & Peterson, 1996). Minors who exchange sex for basic needs or drugs are often runaway and homeless youth; children who have been sexually, physically, or emo- tionally abused; and youth who are unable to find legitimate employment due to a lack of opportunity or education (Curtis et al., 2008). Counseling psy- chologists can advocate for systemic change to support the well-being of Varghese et al. 721 youth and their communities by using information gathered through research initiatives to educate policy makers, law enforcement personnel, and school administrators to prevent the further exploitation of youth. Similarly, coun- seling psychologists could implement programs to ensure that families in marginalized communities receive additional support, because by strengthen- ing the family systems of high-risk youth, their vulnerabilities may be miti- gated, decreasing the likelihood that youth will engage with the justice system and increasing the capacity of families to respond effectively to adverse situ- ations. Counseling psychologists can also provide educators and school administrators with training in order to provide students with culturally responsive and trauma-sensitive classrooms. Training educators in evidence- based interventions, including education as a pathway to reducing recidivism, can help youth graduate from school, develop more effective coping skills, and prevent them from further involvement in the justice system. Taking Action Based on Evidence, Skills, and Values: Challenges and Strategies Taking direct action to advance change is challenging, whether making pol- icy, consulting, or intervening within community or public spheres. In each of these arenas, preparation, experience, credibility, and relationships can promote success. Preparation for making policy can come in the form of psychology-spe- cific experiences such as the APA Congressional Fellowships, as well as through participation in programs that are open to nonpsychologists, such as Empowered to Run. It is likely easier to change policy at local and state lev- els than at the federal level; therefore, getting involved in policies within a city and then moving to state or federal levels would be a realistic strategy. Examples of local offices are the city council, the local school board, or appointed boards and commissions. For example, one way that counseling psychologists can influence policy within correctional agencies is to be appointed to a correctional board. In terms of consultation, not all courts or correctional entities may be open to working with outsiders. Therefore, it will be important to develop positive professional relationships within these systems. Relationships take time to develop, and reforming the justice system from a punitive to a rehabilitative model is a worthy endeavor to invest such time. People’s hearts and minds have to change to see reforms, and counseling psychologists are aware that change happens in the context of building relationships with people to earn their trust. 722 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) Advocating for culturally tailored correctional programs is not easy when social or political forces are encouraging the creation of prisons for profit to mitigate budget shortages in state governments (Hillman, 2019). States with budget deficits may be tempted to accept millions of dollars from companies that operate private prisons (ACLU of Montana, 2017). The dissemination of knowledge and engagement in advocacy are key strategies to overcome such climates. Research and evidence that show the effectiveness of cultur- ally tailored interventions in enhancing public safety as well as their cost- effectiveness can be helpful in advocating for culturally tailored correctional programs. However, community action may be hindered by community members’ systemic distrust due to unjust practices. Without access to these communi- ties, advocates may merely speak for diverse people rather than amplifying their marginalized voices in the service of justice. Therefore, it is important for counseling psychologists to take the time and effort necessary to develop trust and strong collaborative relationships with individuals in marginalized communities. There is a considerable body of literature on community-based participatory research that offers guidance and strategies for relationship development. It is important to have realistic expectations for outcomes of direct action. Implementing evidence-based practices is easier said than done. Counseling psychologists may face many barriers associated with attempting to imple- ment change within large bureaucratic systems. It is inherent in the psychol- ogy of people that a natural tendency exists to resist change. The uncertainty related to whether positive outcomes will or will not be achieved can be chal- lenging for mental health professionals. However, working with a team of collaborators and partners may increase the effectiveness of direct action by drawing on a range of skill sets and multiple circles of influence. Vision: How Would These Actions Promote Justice in the Justice System? Consistent with CRT’s goal of social transformation, the primary goal of systems reform in laws and courts centers on reforming those laws that differentially target and punish People of Color and the poor, including individuals with intersecting marginalized identities. A reformed justice system would change laws and policies that demonstrate blatant disregard for less privileged individuals and their families. A reformed justice sys- tem would treat people equitably in court without showing partiality to the privileged. A reformed court system would stop charging fees and instead Varghese et al. 723 focus on prevention, rehabilitation, and community well-being. Counseling psychologists can help to achieve these goals by advocating for equitable laws and policies, providing research expertise (e.g., demonstrating evi- dence for the effectiveness of preventive and rehabilitative programs), providing education and training for the courts to alleviate bias, and serv- ing in leadership roles, including those roles through which they can help change unjust policies. Goals of justice system reform in law enforcement include nonbiased policing that avoids the violent deaths of People of Color or intersecting identities of disability, gender normativity, and language diversity, espe- cially during and after routine investigative encounters. Reform would result in well-trained, carefully monitored, and effectively supervised law enforcement officers who are able to accurately assess and manage encoun- ters, preventing unnecessary escalation of force. Reform would result in a mentally healthy law enforcement workforce that uses evidence-informed strategies to appropriately and compassionately respond to situations. Finally, law enforcement personnel would earn the trust of diverse com- munities by demonstrating nonbiased policing and transparent examination of all encounters that result in injury or death to community members or law enforcement (The President’s Task Force on 21st Century Policing, 2015). In addition, beyond reform, more progressive approaches to address- ing issues in the justice system may include dismantling the prison indus- trial complex and investing energy and resources in the development of preventive and rehabilitative programs to improve public safety. Counseling psychologists can help achieve these goals by applying their expertise in mental health, diversity, and community collaboration to the training and engagement of law enforcement personnel. Consistent with CRT’s focus on changing structural inequalities and coun- seling psychology’s perspectives on prevention, justice reform could change the very structural inequities that lead to arrest and detention—including poverty, poor nutrition, school discipline, low quality educational experi- ences, and poor housing. For Youth of Color, this would mean distributive and procedural justice in the form of being treated with equity in schools and not be subjected to harsher punishment than their White peers. For adults who are incarcerated, effective reform would include the use of evidence- informed best practices in rehabilitation. A reformed system would not sup- port exploitation and revictimization of People of Color, and would address the needs of especially vulnerable populations such as children and undocu- mented immigrants. Finally, a reformed system would incorporate initiatives to ensure those who leave the correctional system have the requisite skills for successful reentry into society. 724 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) Conclusion Our goal for justice system reform is to have an equitable system that upholds the human rights and dignity of people regardless of background, and is con- sistent with U.S. ideals, as eloquently stated at the conclusion of the U.S. Pledge of Allegiance, “liberty and justice for all” (Independence Hall Association, 1995). This is an ideal yet to be realized—and many individuals’ fundamental rights are still violated in the name of public safety. CRT would have us ask, “Public safety for whom?” Evidence is mounting that public safety increases with equitable justice; in turn, equitable justice relies on enacting rehabilitation strategies rather than overly harsh punishments (see Tow Youth Justice Institute, 2017). Justice reform requires the very best of counseling psychology skills such as advocacy, research expertise, and relationship-building coupled with the highest ideals of the profession, including diversity and social justice. Together, counseling psychologists can be a powerful force for the transfor- mation of the justice system. In this paper, we provided actionable strategies to transform unjust laws, biased courts, racist law enforcement, and dispro- portionately harsh detention. We believe counseling psychologists should use their expertise to achieve these reforms, a foremost human rights issue. Declaration of Conflicting Interests The authors declared no potential conflicts of interest with respect to the research, authorship, and/or publication of this article. Funding The authors received no financial support for the research, authorship, and/or publica- tion of this article. ORCID iD Femina P. Varghese https://orcid.org/0000-0001-6897-3173 References Ackermann, N., Goodman, M. S., Gilbert, K., Arroyo-Johnson, C., & Pagano, M. (2015). Race, law, and health: Examination of ‘Stand Your Ground’ and defendant convictions in Florida. Social Science & Medicine, 142, 194–201. doi:10.1016/j.socscimed.2015.08.012 Aldarondo, E., & Becker, R. (2011). Promoting the well-being of unaccompanied immigrant minors. In L. Buki, & L. Piedra (Eds.), Creating infrastructures for Latino mental health (pp. 195–214). New York, NY: Springer. doi:10.1007/978- 1-4419-9452-3 https://orcid.org/0000-0001-6897-3173 Varghese et al. 725 Altmaier, E. M., & Hansen, J.-I. C. (2012). The Oxford handbook of counseling psy- chology. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. American Civil Liberties Union of Montana. (2017, October). Statement on CoreCivic’s inducement to the state of Montana. Retrieved from https://www .aclumontana.org/en/news/statement-corecivics-inducement-state-montana American Civil Liberties Union of New York. (2019). People v. Jacobs/Mehra v. Kerricks School District (Challenging racial profiling against South Asians in Nassau County). Retrieved from https://www.nyclu.org/en/cases/people-v -jacobsmehra-v-herricks-school-district-challenging-racial-profiling-against -south American Psychological Association. (2012). Presidential task force on immigration. crossroads: The psychology of immigration in the new century. Retrieved from https://www.apa.org/topics/immigration/executive-summary.pdf American Psychological Association. (2014). Report of the Task Force on Trafficking of Women and Girls. Retrieved from https://www.apa.org/pi/women/programs /trafficking/report.pdf American Psychological Association, Commission on Accreditation. (2018). Standards of accreditation for health service psychology. Washington, DC: Author. American Psychological Association. (2017). Multicultural guidelines: An ecological approach to context, identity, and intersectionality. Retrieved from http://www .apa.org/about/policy/multicultural-guidelines.pdf American Psychological Association. (2018a). Committee on Division/APA Relations (CODAPAR): Interdivisional grant program. Retrieved from https://www.apa .org/about/awards/interdivisional-grants-project.aspx?tab=4)f American Psychological Association. (2018b). Legislative issues and advocacy train- ing tools. Retrieved from https://www.apa.org/apags/resources/advocacy/toolkit .aspx?tab=2 Arkansas Act 189, 92d Gen. Assem. (Ark. 2019). Bailey, Z.D., Krieger, N., Agenor, M., Graves, J., Linos, N., & Bassett, M. T. (2017). Structural racism and health inequities in the USA: Evidence and interventions. The Lancet, 389, 1453–1463. doi:10.1016/S0140-6736(17)30569-X Barak, G., Leighton, P., & Cotton, A. (2015). Class, race, gender, crime: The social realities of justice in America (4th ed.). Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield. Bartol, C., & Bartol, A. M. (2017). Criminal behavior: A psychological approach (11th ed.). Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson. Becker Herbst, R., Sabet, R. F., Swanson, A., Suarez, L. G., Marques, D. S., Ameen, E. J., & Aldarondo, E. (2018). “They were going to kill me”: Resilience in unaccompanied immigrant minors. The Counseling Psychologist, 46, 241–268. doi:10.1177/0011000018759769 Beckett, K., & Evans, H. (2015). Crimmigration at the local level: Criminal justice processes in the shadow of deportation. Law & Society Review, 49, 241–277. doi:10.1111/lasr.12120 Benner, K. (2019, July 16). Eric Garner’s death will not lead to federal charges for N.Y.P.D. officer. The New York Times. Retrieved from https://www.nytimes .com/2019/07/16/nyregion/eric-garner-case-death-daniel-pantaleo.html https://www.aclumontana.org/en/news/statement-corecivics-inducement-state-montana https://www.aclumontana.org/en/news/statement-corecivics-inducement-state-montana https://www.nyclu.org/en/cases/people-v-jacobsmehra-v-herricks-school-district-challenging-racial-profiling-against-south https://www.nyclu.org/en/cases/people-v-jacobsmehra-v-herricks-school-district-challenging-racial-profiling-against-south https://www.nyclu.org/en/cases/people-v-jacobsmehra-v-herricks-school-district-challenging-racial-profiling-against-south https://www.apa.org/topics/immigration/executive-summary.pdf https://www.apa.org/pi/women/programs/trafficking/report.pdf https://www.apa.org/pi/women/programs/trafficking/report.pdf http://www.apa.org/about/policy/multicultural-guidelines.pdf http://www.apa.org/about/policy/multicultural-guidelines.pdf https://www.apa.org/about/awards/interdivisional-grants-project.aspx?tab=4)f https://www.apa.org/about/awards/interdivisional-grants-project.aspx?tab=4)f https://www.apa.org/apags/resources/advocacy/toolkit.aspx?tab=2 https://www.apa.org/apags/resources/advocacy/toolkit.aspx?tab=2 https://www.nytimes.com/2019/07/16/nyregion/eric-garner-case-death-daniel-pantaleo.html https://www.nytimes.com/2019/07/16/nyregion/eric-garner-case-death-daniel-pantaleo.html 726 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) Birzer, M. L. (1999). Police training in the 21st century. FBI Law Enforcement Bulletin, 68(7), 16–19. doi:10.1037/e313152004-005 Black lives upended by policing: The raw videos sparking outrage. (2018, April 19). The New York Times. Retrieved from https://www.nytimes.com/interactive/2017/08/19 /us/police-videos-race.html?mtrref=www.google.com&assetType=REGIWALL& mtrref=www.nytimes.com&gwh=2B5573F635DAB0218BAAC936DE22B280&g wt=pay&assetType=REGIWALL Blackmon, D. A. (2009). Slavery by another name: The re-enslavement of Black Americans from the Civil War to World War II. New York, NY: Doubleday. Blomberg, T. G., Bales, W. D., & Piquero, A. R. (2012). Is educational achievement a turning point for incarcerated delinquents across race and sex? Journal of Youth and Adolescence, 41, 202–216. doi:10.1007/s10964-011-9680-4 Bonnie, R. J., Johnson, R. L., Chemers, B. M., & Schuck, J. (2013). Reforming juve- nile justice: A developmental approach. Washington, DC: National Academies Press. Bonta, J., & Andrews, D. A. (2017). The psychology of criminal conduct (6th ed.). New York, NY: Routledge. Bor, J., Venkataramani, A. S., Williams, D. R., & Tsai, A. C. (2018). Police killings and their spillover effects on the mental health of Black Americans: A popula- tion-based, quasi-experimental study. The Lancet, 392, 302–310. doi:10.1016/ S0140-6736(18)31130-9 Brunson, R. K., & Miller, J. (2006). Young Black men and urban policing in the U.S. The British Journal of Criminology, 46, 613–640. doi:10.1093/bjc/azi093 Byrne, O., & Miller, E. (2012, March). The flow of unaccompanied children through the immigration system: A resource for practitioners, policy makers, and research- ers. Retrieved from https://storage.googleapis.com/vera-web-assets/downloads /Publications/the-flow-of-unaccompanied-children-through-the-immigration-system -a-resource-for-practitioners-policy-makers-and-researchers/legacy_downloads/the -flow-of-unaccompanied-children-through-the-immigration-system.pdf Carson, E.A. (2015). Prisoners in 2014 (NCJ 248955). Retrieved from https://www .bjs.gov/content/pub/pdf/p14.pdf Carter, R. T. (2007). Racism and psychological and emotional injury: Recognizing and assessing race-based traumatic stress. The Counseling Psychologist, 35, 13– 105. doi:10.1177/0011000006292033 Carter, R. T., Lau, M. Y., Johnson, V., & Kirkinis, K. (2017). Racial discrimina- tion and health outcomes among racial/ethnic minorities: A meta-analytic review. Journal of Multicultural Counseling and Development, 45, 232–259. doi:10.1002/jmcd.12076 Case, A., & Bhattacharya, J. (2017, May). Driving into debt: The need for traffic ticket fee reform. Insight Center for Community and Economic Development. Retrieved from https://insightcced.org/driving-into-debt-the-need-for-traffic -ticket-fee-reform Center for American Progress & Movement Advancement Project. (2016). Unjust: How the broken justice system fails LGBTQ People of Color. Retrieved from http://www.lgbtmap.org/policy-and-issue-analysis/criminal-justice-poc https://www.nytimes.com/interactive/2017/08/19/us/police-videos-race.html?mtrref=www.google.com&assetType=REGIWALL&mtrref=www.nytimes.com&gwh=2B5573F635DAB0218BAAC936DE22B280&gwt=pay&assetType=REGIWALL https://www.nytimes.com/interactive/2017/08/19/us/police-videos-race.html?mtrref=www.google.com&assetType=REGIWALL&mtrref=www.nytimes.com&gwh=2B5573F635DAB0218BAAC936DE22B280&gwt=pay&assetType=REGIWALL https://www.nytimes.com/interactive/2017/08/19/us/police-videos-race.html?mtrref=www.google.com&assetType=REGIWALL&mtrref=www.nytimes.com&gwh=2B5573F635DAB0218BAAC936DE22B280&gwt=pay&assetType=REGIWALL https://www.nytimes.com/interactive/2017/08/19/us/police-videos-race.html?mtrref=www.google.com&assetType=REGIWALL&mtrref=www.nytimes.com&gwh=2B5573F635DAB0218BAAC936DE22B280&gwt=pay&assetType=REGIWALL https://storage.googleapis.com/vera-web-assets/downloads/Publications/the-flow-of-unaccompanied-children-through-the-immigration-system-a-resource-for-practitioners-policy-makers-and-researchers/legacy_downloads/the-flow-of-unaccompanied-children-through-the-immigration-system.pdf https://storage.googleapis.com/vera-web-assets/downloads/Publications/the-flow-of-unaccompanied-children-through-the-immigration-system-a-resource-for-practitioners-policy-makers-and-researchers/legacy_downloads/the-flow-of-unaccompanied-children-through-the-immigration-system.pdf https://storage.googleapis.com/vera-web-assets/downloads/Publications/the-flow-of-unaccompanied-children-through-the-immigration-system-a-resource-for-practitioners-policy-makers-and-researchers/legacy_downloads/the-flow-of-unaccompanied-children-through-the-immigration-system.pdf https://storage.googleapis.com/vera-web-assets/downloads/Publications/the-flow-of-unaccompanied-children-through-the-immigration-system-a-resource-for-practitioners-policy-makers-and-researchers/legacy_downloads/the-flow-of-unaccompanied-children-through-the-immigration-system.pdf https://www.bjs.gov/content/pub/pdf/p14.pdf https://www.bjs.gov/content/pub/pdf/p14.pdf https://insightcced.org/driving-into-debt-the-need-for-traffic-ticket-fee-reform https://insightcced.org/driving-into-debt-the-need-for-traffic-ticket-fee-reform http://www.lgbtmap.org/policy-and-issue-analysis/criminal-justice-poc Varghese et al. 727 Chacón, J. M. (2012). Overcriminalizing immigration. Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 102, 613–652. Chakraborly, R. (2018, January 3). Civil disobedience in the Trump Era. Harvard Political Review. Retrieved from http://harvardpolitics.com/united-states/civil -disobedience-in-the-trump-era/ Chism, E. (2016). Police officer perceptions of wellness programs (Doctoral disserta- tion). Retrieved from https://scholarworks.waldenu.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?arti cle=4250&context=dissertations Clark, R., Anderson, N. B., Clark, V. R., & Williams, D. R. (1999). Racism as a stressor for African Americans: A biopsychosocial model. American Psychologist, 54, 805–816. doi:10.1037/0003-066X.54.10.805 Clawson, H. J., Salomon, A., & Grace, L. G. (2008). Treating the hidden wounds: Trauma treatment and mental health recovery for victims of human trafficking. Retrieved from http://aspe.hhs.gov/hsp/07/humantrafficking/treating/ib.pdf Coderoni, G. R. (2002). The relationship between multicultural training for police and effective law enforcement. FBI Law Enforcement Bulletin, 71(11), 16– 18. Retrieved from https://heinonline.org/HOL/Page?handle=hein.journals /fbileb71&div=77&g_sent=1&casa_token=tsLetCquQAYAAAAA:rQjQCHc dOLkBl0c3ET4m9L6D3x-QFqL0ysB6v6s9QQE0VarPHM_PqLj_xeKLLkU YwJhNOMOR&collection=journals Collins, J. C., & Rocco, T. S. (2015). Rules of engagement as survival consciousness: Gay male law enforcement officers’ experiential learning in a masculinized indus- try. Adult Education Quarterly, 65, 295–312. doi:10.1177/0741713615585163 Community Toolbox: Learning a Skill. (2018). Changing policies: An overview. Retrieved from https://ctb.ku.edu/en/table-of-contents/implement/changing -policies/overview/main Compton, M. T., Bahora, M., Watson, A. C., & Oliva, J. R. (2008). A comprehensive review of extant research on crisis intervention team (CIT) program. Journal of the American Academy of Psychiatry and the Law Online, 36(1), 47–55. Retrieved from http://www.jaapl.org/cgi/content/full/36/1/47 Coonan, T., & Thompson, R. (2003). Florida responds to human trafficking. Florida State University Center for the Advancement of Human Rights. Retrieved from https://cahr.fsu.edu/wp-content/uploads/2018/01/thereport.pdf Cornett-DeVito, M. M., & McGlone, E. L. (2000). Multicultural communication training for law enforcement officers: A case study. Criminal Justice Policy Review, 11, 234–253. doi:10.1177/0887403400011003003 Council of Economic Advisors. (2015, December). Fines, fees, and bail: Payment in the criminal justice system that disproportionately impact the poor. Retrieved from https://obamaWhitehouse.archives.gov/sites/default/files/page/files/1215_ cea_fine_fee_bail_issue_brief.pdf Covenant House. (2013). Homelessness, survival sex, and human trafficking: As experienced by the youth of Covenant House New York. New York, NY: Bigelson. Retrieved from https://humantraffickinghotline.org/sites/default /files/Homelessness%2C%20Survival%20Sex%2C%20and%20Human%20 Trafficking%20-%20Covenant%20House%20NY.pdf http://harvardpolitics.com/united-states/civil-disobedience-in-the-trump-era/ http://harvardpolitics.com/united-states/civil-disobedience-in-the-trump-era/ https://scholarworks.waldenu.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=4250&context=dissertations https://scholarworks.waldenu.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=4250&context=dissertations http://aspe.hhs.gov/hsp/07/humantrafficking/treating/ib.pdf https://heinonline.org/HOL/Page?handle=hein.journals/fbileb71&div=77&g_sent=1&casa_token=tsLetCquQAYAAAAA:rQjQCHcdOLkBl0c3ET4m9L6D3x-QFqL0ysB6v6s9QQE0VarPHM_PqLj_xeKLLkUYwJhNOMOR&collection=journals https://heinonline.org/HOL/Page?handle=hein.journals/fbileb71&div=77&g_sent=1&casa_token=tsLetCquQAYAAAAA:rQjQCHcdOLkBl0c3ET4m9L6D3x-QFqL0ysB6v6s9QQE0VarPHM_PqLj_xeKLLkUYwJhNOMOR&collection=journals https://heinonline.org/HOL/Page?handle=hein.journals/fbileb71&div=77&g_sent=1&casa_token=tsLetCquQAYAAAAA:rQjQCHcdOLkBl0c3ET4m9L6D3x-QFqL0ysB6v6s9QQE0VarPHM_PqLj_xeKLLkUYwJhNOMOR&collection=journals https://heinonline.org/HOL/Page?handle=hein.journals/fbileb71&div=77&g_sent=1&casa_token=tsLetCquQAYAAAAA:rQjQCHcdOLkBl0c3ET4m9L6D3x-QFqL0ysB6v6s9QQE0VarPHM_PqLj_xeKLLkUYwJhNOMOR&collection=journals https://ctb.ku.edu/en/table-of-contents/implement/changing-policies/overview/main https://ctb.ku.edu/en/table-of-contents/implement/changing-policies/overview/main http://www.jaapl.org/cgi/content/full/36/1/47 https://cahr.fsu.edu/wp-content/uploads/2018/01/thereport.pdf https://obamaWhitehouse.archives.gov/sites/default/files/page/files/1215_cea_fine_fee_bail_issue_brief.pdf https://obamaWhitehouse.archives.gov/sites/default/files/page/files/1215_cea_fine_fee_bail_issue_brief.pdf https://humantraffickinghotline.org/sites/default/files/Homelessness%2C%20Survival%20Sex%2C%20and%20Human%20Trafficking%20-%20Covenant%20House%20NY.pdf https://humantraffickinghotline.org/sites/default/files/Homelessness%2C%20Survival%20Sex%2C%20and%20Human%20Trafficking%20-%20Covenant%20House%20NY.pdf https://humantraffickinghotline.org/sites/default/files/Homelessness%2C%20Survival%20Sex%2C%20and%20Human%20Trafficking%20-%20Covenant%20House%20NY.pdf 728 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) Crenshaw, K. (1991). Mapping the margins: Intersectionality, identity politics, and violence against Women of Color. Stanford Law Review, 43, 1241–1299. doi:10.2307/1229039 Crenshaw, K. (2011). Twenty years of Critical Race Theory: Looking back to move forward. Connecticut Law Review, 43, 1253–1352. Crenshaw, K., Ritchie, A. J., Anspach, R., Gilmer, R., & Harris, L. (2015, July). Say her name: Resisting police brutality against Black women. African American Policy Reform. Retrieved from http://static1.squarespace.com/static/53f20d90e 4b0b80451158d8c/t/55a810d7e4b058f342f55873/1437077719984/AAPF_ SMN_Brief_full_singles.compressed.pdf Criminal Justice Policy Foundation. (2018). Mandatory minimums and sentencing reform. Retrieved from https://www.cjpf.org/mandatory-minimums/ Criminal Justice Project. (2017). Death Row U.S.A. Retrieved from http://www .naacpldf.org/files/about-us/DRUSASpring2017.pdf Curtis, R., Terry, K., Dank, M., Dombrowski, K., & Khan, B. (2008). The commercial sexual exploitation of children in New York City (Vol. 1). Retrieved from https:// www.ncjrs.gov/pdffiles1/nij/grants/225083.pdf Dank, M., Yahner, J., Madden, K., Banuelos, I., Yu, L., Ritchie, A., Mora, M., & Conner, B. (2015). Surviving the streets of New York: Experiences of LGBTQ youth, YMSM, and YWSW engaged in survival sex. Retrieved from http://www .urban.org/sites/default/files/alfresco/publication-pdfs/2000119-Surviving-the -Streets-of-New-York.pdf Darensburg, T., Andrew, M. E., Hartley, T. A., Burchfiel, C. M., Fekedulegn, D., & Violanti, J. M. (2006). Gender and age differences in posttraumatic stress disor- der and depression among Buffalo police officers. Traumatology, 12, 220–228. doi:10.1177/1534765606296271 David, E. J. R. (2013). Internalized oppression: The psychology of marginalized groups. New York, NY: Springer. Davis, L. M., Bozick, R., Steele, J. L., Saunders, J., & Miles, J. N. V. (2013) Evaluating the effectiveness of correctional education: A meta-analysis of programs that provide education to incarcerated adults. Retrieved from https://www.rand.org /pubs/research_reports/RR266.html Deer, S. (2010). Relocation revisited: Sex trafficking of native women in the United States. William Mitchell Law Review. Retrieved from https://open.mitchellhamline .edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1157&context=facsch Delgado, R., & Stefancic, J. (2017). Critical Race Theory: An introduction (3rd ed.). New York, NY: New York University. Dreier, P. (2016, July 11). Caught on camera: Police racism. The American Prospect. Retrieved from http://prospect.org/article/caught-camera-police-racism Dressel, J., & Farid, H. (2018). The accuracy, fairness, and limits of predicting recidi- vism. Science Advances, 4(1), eaao5580. doi:10.1126/sciadv.aao5580 Dwyer, J. (2004). Illegal immigrants, health care, and social responsibility. The Hastings Center Report, 34(1), 34–41. doi:10.2307/3528249 Edelman, M. W. (2007). The cradle to prison pipeline: An American crisis. Preventing Chronic Disease, CDC, 4(3), A43. Retrieved from https://www.cdc.gov/pcd/issues /2007/jul/07_0038.htm http://static1.squarespace.com/static/53f20d90e4b0b80451158d8c/t/55a810d7e4b058f342f55873/1437077719984/AAPF_SMN_Brief_full_singles.compressed.pdf http://static1.squarespace.com/static/53f20d90e4b0b80451158d8c/t/55a810d7e4b058f342f55873/1437077719984/AAPF_SMN_Brief_full_singles.compressed.pdf http://static1.squarespace.com/static/53f20d90e4b0b80451158d8c/t/55a810d7e4b058f342f55873/1437077719984/AAPF_SMN_Brief_full_singles.compressed.pdf https://www.cjpf.org/mandatory-minimums/ http://www.naacpldf.org/files/about-us/DRUSASpring2017.pdf http://www.naacpldf.org/files/about-us/DRUSASpring2017.pdf https://www.ncjrs.gov/pdffiles1/nij/grants/225083.pdf https://www.ncjrs.gov/pdffiles1/nij/grants/225083.pdf http://www.urban.org/sites/default/files/alfresco/publication-pdfs/2000119-Surviving-the-Streets-of-New-York.pdf http://www.urban.org/sites/default/files/alfresco/publication-pdfs/2000119-Surviving-the-Streets-of-New-York.pdf http://www.urban.org/sites/default/files/alfresco/publication-pdfs/2000119-Surviving-the-Streets-of-New-York.pdf https://www.rand.org/pubs/research_reports/RR266.html https://www.rand.org/pubs/research_reports/RR266.html https://open.mitchellhamline.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1157&context=facsch https://open.mitchellhamline.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1157&context=facsch http://prospect.org/article/caught-camera-police-racism https://www.cdc.gov/pcd/issues/2007/jul/07_0038.htm https://www.cdc.gov/pcd/issues/2007/jul/07_0038.htm Varghese et al. 729 Estes, R., & Weiner, N. (2001). The commercial sexual exploitation of children in the U.S., Canada and Mexico. Retrieved from https://abolitionistmom.org/wp -content/uploads/2014/05/Complete_CSEC_0estes-weiner.pdf Ewing, W. A. (2012). Opportunity and exclusion: A brief history of U.S. immi- gration policy. Immigration Policy Center. Retrieved from https://www .americanimmigrationcouncil.org/sites/default/files/research/opportunity_ exclusion_011312.pdf Fazel, S., Hayes, A. J., Bartellas, K., Clerici, M., & Trestman, R. (2016). Mental health of prisoners: Prevalence, adverse outcomes, and interventions. The Lancet Psychiatry, 3, 871–881. doi:10.1016/s2215-0366(16)30142-0 Federal Judicial Center. (2019). Federal and state court cooperation: Effectiveness of implicit bias trainings. Retrieved from https://www.fjc.gov/content/337738 /effectiveness-implicit-bias-trainings Finklea, K., Fernandes-Alcantara, A., & Siskin, A. (2015, January 28). Sex trafficking of children in the United States: Overview and issues for Congress. Retrieved from https://fas.org/sgp/crs/misc/R41878.pdf First Step Act of 2018, S. 115-391, 115th Cong. (2018). Ford, D. (2015, July 21). New video shows Sandra Bland’s arrest. CNN. Retrieved from https://www.cnn.com/2015/07/21/us/texas-sandra-bland-arrest/index.html Fournier, J. (2018). 5 examples of civil disobedience we can learn from in 2018. Feministing. Retrieved from http://feministing.com/2018/01/08/5-examples-of -civil-disobedience-we-can-learn-from-in-2018/ Fridell, L. (2017). Producing bias-free policing: A science-based approach. New York, NY: Springer Publishing and the George Mason University Center for Evidence-Based Criminology. Fuchs, C. (2016, May 13). Charges dropped for Alabama cop who partially paralyzed grandfather. NBC News. Retrieved from https://www.nbcnews.com/news/asian -america/assault-charges-dropped-alabama-cop-who-partially-paralyzed-indian -grandfather-n573806 Gerassi, L. (2015). From exploitation to industry: Definitions, risks, and conse- quences of domestic sexual exploitation and sex work among women and girls. Journal of Human Behavior in the Social Environment, 25, 591–605. doi:10.108 0/10911359.2014.991055 Gokavi, M. (2016, August 13). Judge finds probable cause for 911 caller in Crawford shooting. Dayton Daily News. Retrieved from https://www.daytondailynews .com/news/crime–law/judge-finds-probable-cause-for-911-caller-crawford -shooting/HdlR8ZsgOnjnLTRhG6KVRM/ Galovski, T. E., Peterson, Z. D., Beagley, M. C., Strasshofer, D. R., Held, P., & Fletcher, T. D. (2016). Exposure to violence during Ferguson protests: Mental health effects for law enforcement and community members. Journal of Traumatic Stress, 29, 283–292. doi:10.1002/jts.22105 Gone, J. P., Hartmann, W. E., Pomerville, A., Wendt, D. C., Klem, S. H., & Burrage, R. L. (2019). The impact of historical trauma on health outcomes for indig- enous populations in the USA and Canada: A systematic review. American Psychologist, 74, 20–35. doi:10.1037/amp0000338 https://abolitionistmom.org/wp-content/uploads/2014/05/Complete_CSEC_0estes-weiner.pdf https://abolitionistmom.org/wp-content/uploads/2014/05/Complete_CSEC_0estes-weiner.pdf https://www.americanimmigrationcouncil.org/sites/default/files/research/opportunity_exclusion_011312.pdf https://www.americanimmigrationcouncil.org/sites/default/files/research/opportunity_exclusion_011312.pdf https://www.americanimmigrationcouncil.org/sites/default/files/research/opportunity_exclusion_011312.pdf https://www.fjc.gov/content/337738/effectiveness-implicit-bias-trainings https://www.fjc.gov/content/337738/effectiveness-implicit-bias-trainings https://fas.org/sgp/crs/misc/R41878.pdf https://www.cnn.com/2015/07/21/us/texas-sandra-bland-arrest/index.html http://feministing.com/2018/01/08/5-examples-of-civil-disobedience-we-can-learn-from-in-2018/ http://feministing.com/2018/01/08/5-examples-of-civil-disobedience-we-can-learn-from-in-2018/ https://www.nbcnews.com/news/asian-america/assault-charges-dropped-alabama-cop-who-partially-paralyzed-indian-grandfather-n573806 https://www.nbcnews.com/news/asian-america/assault-charges-dropped-alabama-cop-who-partially-paralyzed-indian-grandfather-n573806 https://www.nbcnews.com/news/asian-america/assault-charges-dropped-alabama-cop-who-partially-paralyzed-indian-grandfather-n573806 https://www.daytondailynews.com/news/crime%E2%80%93law/judge-finds-probable-cause-for-911-caller-crawford-shooting/HdlR8ZsgOnjnLTRhG6KVRM/ https://www.daytondailynews.com/news/crime%E2%80%93law/judge-finds-probable-cause-for-911-caller-crawford-shooting/HdlR8ZsgOnjnLTRhG6KVRM/ https://www.daytondailynews.com/news/crime%E2%80%93law/judge-finds-probable-cause-for-911-caller-crawford-shooting/HdlR8ZsgOnjnLTRhG6KVRM/ 730 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) Gonzales, R. G., Suárez-Orozco, C., & Dedios-Sanguineti, M. A. (2013). No place to belong: Contextualizing concepts of mental health among undocumented immigrant youth in the U.S. American Behavioral Scientist, 57, 1174–1199. doi:10.1177/0002764213487349 Gonzales, S. (2016, October 11). Nearly 90% of New Jersey children tried as adults since 2011 were Black or Latino. The Guardian. Retrieved from https://www .theguardian.com/us-news/2016/oct/11/new-jersey-juvenile-detention-minority -tried-adults Gotsch, K., & Basti, V. (2018). Capitalizing on mass incarceration: U.S. growth in private prisons. The Sentencing Project. Retrieved from https://www .sentencingproject.org/publications/capitalizing-on-mass-incarceration-u-s -growth-in-private-prisons/ Gramlich, J. (2018). The gap between the number of Blacks and Whites in prison is shrinking. Pew Research Center. Retrieved from https://www.pewresearch.org /fact-tank/2019/04/30/shrinking-gap-between-number-of-blacks-and-whites-in -prison/ Gramlich, J., & Bialik, K. (2017). Immigration offenses make up a growing share of federal arrests. Pew Research Center. Retrieved from http://www.pewresearch .org/fact-tank/2017/04/10/immigration-offenses-make-up-a-growing-share-of -federal-arrests/ Grant applications — minority impact statements. (2018, December 8). Retrieved from https://www.legis.iowa.gov/docs/code/8.11.pdf Hacker, K., Chu, J., Leung, C., Marra, R., Pirie, A., Brahimi, M., . . . Marlin, R. P. (2011). The impact of immigration and customs enforcement on immigrant health: Perceptions of immigrants in Everett, Massachusetts, USA. Social Science & Medicine, 73, 586–594. doi:10.1016/j.socscimed.2011.06.007 Hannah-Moffat, K. (2018). Algorithmic risk governance: Big data analytics, race and information activism in criminal justice debates. Theoretical Criminology, 23, 453–470. doi:10.1177/1362480618763582 Hargons, C., Mosley, D., Falconer, J., Faloughi, R., Singh, A., Stevens-Watkins, D., & Cokley, K. (2017). Black lives matter: A call to action for counsel- ing psychology leaders. The Counseling Psychologist, 45, 873–901. doi:10. 1177/0011000017733048 Heilbrun, K., DeMatteo, D., Yasuhara, K., Brooks-Holliday, S., Shah, S., King, C., . . . Laduke, C. (2012). Community-based alternatives for justice-involved individuals with severe mental illness review of the relevant research. Criminal Justice and Behavior, 39, 351–419. doi:10.1177/0093854811432421 Hennessy, S. (2001). Cultural awareness and communication training: What works and what doesn’t. The Police Chief, 68(11), 15–19. Retrieved from https://www .ncjrs.gov/App/Publications/abstract.aspx?ID=192749 Hillman, A. (2019, February). Among Dunleavy’s proposed DOC cuts, sending 500 prisoners out of state. Alaska Public Media. Retrieved from https://www .alaskapublic.org/2019/02/13/among-dunleavys-proposed-doc-cuts-sending -500-prisoners-out-of-state/ https://www.theguardian.com/us-news/2016/oct/11/new-jersey-juvenile-detention-minority-tried-adults https://www.theguardian.com/us-news/2016/oct/11/new-jersey-juvenile-detention-minority-tried-adults https://www.theguardian.com/us-news/2016/oct/11/new-jersey-juvenile-detention-minority-tried-adults https://www.sentencingproject.org/publications/capitalizing-on-mass-incarceration-u-s-growth-in-private-prisons/ https://www.sentencingproject.org/publications/capitalizing-on-mass-incarceration-u-s-growth-in-private-prisons/ https://www.sentencingproject.org/publications/capitalizing-on-mass-incarceration-u-s-growth-in-private-prisons/ https://www.pewresearch.org/fact-tank/2019/04/30/shrinking-gap-between-number-of-blacks-and-whites-in-prison/ https://www.pewresearch.org/fact-tank/2019/04/30/shrinking-gap-between-number-of-blacks-and-whites-in-prison/ https://www.pewresearch.org/fact-tank/2019/04/30/shrinking-gap-between-number-of-blacks-and-whites-in-prison/ http://www.pewresearch.org/fact-tank/2017/04/10/immigration-offenses-make-up-a-growing-share-of-federal-arrests/ http://www.pewresearch.org/fact-tank/2017/04/10/immigration-offenses-make-up-a-growing-share-of-federal-arrests/ http://www.pewresearch.org/fact-tank/2017/04/10/immigration-offenses-make-up-a-growing-share-of-federal-arrests/ https://www.legis.iowa.gov/docs/code/8.11.pdf https://www.ncjrs.gov/App/Publications/abstract.aspx?ID=192749 https://www.ncjrs.gov/App/Publications/abstract.aspx?ID=192749 https://www.alaskapublic.org/2019/02/13/among-dunleavys-proposed-doc-cuts-sending-500-prisoners-out-of-state/ https://www.alaskapublic.org/2019/02/13/among-dunleavys-proposed-doc-cuts-sending-500-prisoners-out-of-state/ https://www.alaskapublic.org/2019/02/13/among-dunleavys-proposed-doc-cuts-sending-500-prisoners-out-of-state/ Varghese et al. 731 Hinton, E. (2016) From the war on poverty to the war on crime: The making of mass incarceration in America. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Hockenberry, S., & Puzzanchera, C. (2018). Juvenile court statistics 2015. National Center for Juvenile Justice. Retrieved from https://www.ojjdp.gov/ojstatbb /njcda/pdf/jcs2015.pdf Hoffmann, J. P., Erickson, L. D., & Spence, K. R. (2013). Modeling the associa- tion between academic achievement and delinquency: An application of interac- tional theory. Criminology: An Interdisciplinary Journal, 51, 629–660. doi:10. 1111/1745-9125.12014 Immigration and Nationality Act of 1965, 79 U.S.C. §§ 202 212 et seq. (1968). Retrieved from http://legislink.org/us/pl-89-236 Independence Hall Association. (1995). Historic documents: The pledge of alle- giance. Retrieved from http://www.ushistory.org/documents/pledge.htm Iles, G., & Adegun, O. V. (2018). Geography and sentencing: Does country of citi- zenship influence sentence longevity? International Journal of Criminology and Sociology, 7, 48–58. doi:10.6000/1929-4409.2018.07.05 Israel, T., Bettergarcia, J. N., Delucio, K., Avellar, T. R., Harkness, A., & Goodman, J. A. (2017). Reactions of law enforcement to LGBTQ diversity training. Human Resource Development Quarterly, 28, 197–226. doi:10.1002/hrdq.21281 Israel, T., Harkness, A., Avellar, T. R., Delucio, K., Bettergarcia, J. N., & Goodman, J. A. (2016). LGBTQ-affirming policing: Tactics generated by law enforcement personnel. Journal of Police and Criminal Psychology, 31, 173–181. doi:10.1007/ s11896-015-9169-2 Jacobson, L. (2018, January 22). School-university partnership seeks to improve graduation rates. Education Dive. Retrieved from https://www.educationdive.com /news/school-university-partnership-seeks-to-improve-graduation-rates/515058/ James, D. J., & Glaze, L. E. (2006). Mental health problems of prison and jail inmates. Retrieved from https://www.bjs.gov/content/pub/pdf/mhppji.pdf James, L., Fridell, L., & Straub, F. (2016, February). Psychosocial factors impact- ing on officers’ decisions to use deadly force: The implicit bias v. “Ferguson” effects. The Police Chief. Retrieved from http://www.policechiefmagazine.org /implicit-bias-versus-the-ferguson-effect-psychosocial-factors-impacting-officers -decisions-to-use-deadly-force/ Joint Public Statement by Psychology Groups on U.S. Immigration Policies and Practices. (2018, July 3). Retrieved from http://helenneville1.wixsite.com/website-1 Jones, C. P. (2000). Levels of racism: A theoretic framework and a gardener’s tale. American Journal of Public Health, 90, 1212–1215. doi:10.2105/AJPH.90.8.1212 Jones, J., & Podkul, J. (2012, October). Forced from home: The lost boys and girls of Central America. Report by the Women’s Refugee Commission. Retrieved from https://www.womensrefugeecommission.org/uncategorized/2057-forced-from -home-the-lost-boys-and-girls-of-central-america-background-and-report\ Jordan, M. (2019, July 30). No more family separations, except these 900. New York Times. Retrieved from https://www.nytimes.com/2019/07/30/us/migrant-family -separations.html https://www.ojjdp.gov/ojstatbb/njcda/pdf/jcs2015.pdf https://www.ojjdp.gov/ojstatbb/njcda/pdf/jcs2015.pdf http://legislink.org/us/pl-89-236 http://www.ushistory.org/documents/pledge.htm https://www.educationdive.com/news/school-university-partnership-seeks-to-improve-graduation-rates/515058/ https://www.educationdive.com/news/school-university-partnership-seeks-to-improve-graduation-rates/515058/ https://www.bjs.gov/content/pub/pdf/mhppji.pdf http://www.policechiefmagazine.org/implicit-bias-versus-the-ferguson-effect-psychosocial-factors-impacting-officers-decisions-to-use-deadly-force/ http://www.policechiefmagazine.org/implicit-bias-versus-the-ferguson-effect-psychosocial-factors-impacting-officers-decisions-to-use-deadly-force/ http://www.policechiefmagazine.org/implicit-bias-versus-the-ferguson-effect-psychosocial-factors-impacting-officers-decisions-to-use-deadly-force/ http://helenneville1.wixsite.com/website-1 https://www.womensrefugeecommission.org/uncategorized/2057-forced-from-home-the-lost-boys-and-girls-of-central-america-background-and-report https://www.womensrefugeecommission.org/uncategorized/2057-forced-from-home-the-lost-boys-and-girls-of-central-america-background-and-report https://www.nytimes.com/2019/07/30/us/migrant-family-separations.html https://www.nytimes.com/2019/07/30/us/migrant-family-separations.html 732 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) Justifiable Use of Force, No. 776.013 Fla. Laws. (2019). Retrieved from http://www .leg.state.fl.us/statutes/index.cfm?App_mode=Display_Statute&URL= 0700-0799/0776/0776.html Juszkiewicz, J. (2007, October). Too many youth caught in the net of adult pros- ecution. Retrieved from http://www.campaignforyouthjustice.org/research/cfyj -reports/item/too-many-youth-caught-in-the-net-of-adult-prosecution KATV News. (2017, August 10). UCA, juvenile court & judge join forces to help at- risk youth. Retrieved from https://katv.com/news/local/uca-juvenile-court-judge -join-forces-to-help-at-risk-youth Kennealy, P. J., Skeem, J. L., Manchak, S. M., & Louden, J. E. (2012). Firm, fair, and caring officer-offender relationships protect against supervision failure. Law and Human Behavior, 36, 496–505. doi:10.1037/h0093935 Klockars, C. B., Ivkovich, S. K., Harver, W. E., & Haberfeld, M. R. (2000). The measurement of police integrity (NCJ 181465). Retrieved from https://www.ncjrs .gov/pdffiles1/nij/181465.pdf Krisberg, B. A. (2018). Juvenile justice and delinquency. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Krivo, L. J., & Peterson, R. D. (1996). Extremely disadvantaged neighborhoods and urban crime. Social Forces, 75, 619–648. doi:10.1093/sf/75.2.619 Krogstad, J. M., Passel, J. S., & Cohn, D. (2019, June 12). 5 Facts about illegal immigrants in the U.S. Retrieved from https://www.pewresearch.org/fact-tank /2019/06/12/5-facts-about-illegal-immigration-in-the-u-s/ Landers, M., McGrath, K., Johnson, M. H., Armstrong, M. I., & Dollard, N. (2017). Baseline characteristics of dependent youth who have been commercially sexu- ally exploited: Findings from a specialized treatment program. Journal of Child Sex Abuse, 26, 692–709. doi:10.1080/10538712.2017.1323814 Lavoie, J., Dickerson, K. L., Redlich, A. D., & Quas, J. A. (2019). Overcoming disclosure reluctance in youth victims of sex trafficking: New directions for research, policy, and practice. Psychology, Public Policy, and Law, 25, 225–238. doi:10.1037/law0000205 Lee, D. L., & Ahn, S. (2012). Discrimination against Latina/os: A meta-analysis of individual-level resources and outcomes. The Counseling Psychologist, 40, 28– 65. doi:10.1177/0011000011403326 Levinson, J. D., Bennett, M. W., & Hioki, K. (2017). Judging implicit bias: A national empirical study of judicial stereotypes. Florida Law Review, 69(1), 63–114. Retrieved from https://heinonline.org/HOL/Page?collection=journals&handle=h ein.journals/uflr69&id=69&men_tab=srchresults Li, Y., & Lerner, R. M. (2011). Trajectories of school engagement during adoles- cence: Implications for grades, depression, delinquency, and substance use. Developmental Psychology, 47, 233–247. doi:10.1037/a0021307 Lichtenberg, J. W., Hutman, H., & Goodyear, R. K. (2018). Portrait of counseling psychology: Demographics, roles, activities, and values across three decades. The Counseling Psychologist, 46, 50–76. doi:10.1177/0011000018754532 Lynch, S., & Cook, N. (2018, June 7). Exclusive: U.S. sending 1,600 immigration detainees to federal prisons. Retrieved from https://www.reuters.com/article http://www.leg.state.fl.us/statutes/index.cfm?App_mode=Display_Statute&URL=0700-0799/0776/0776.html http://www.leg.state.fl.us/statutes/index.cfm?App_mode=Display_Statute&URL=0700-0799/0776/0776.html http://www.leg.state.fl.us/statutes/index.cfm?App_mode=Display_Statute&URL=0700-0799/0776/0776.html http://www.campaignforyouthjustice.org/research/cfyj-reports/item/too-many-youth-caught-in-the-net-of-adult-prosecution http://www.campaignforyouthjustice.org/research/cfyj-reports/item/too-many-youth-caught-in-the-net-of-adult-prosecution https://katv.com/news/local/uca-juvenile-court-judge-join-forces-to-help-at-risk-youth https://katv.com/news/local/uca-juvenile-court-judge-join-forces-to-help-at-risk-youth https://www.ncjrs.gov/pdffiles1/nij/181465.pdf https://www.ncjrs.gov/pdffiles1/nij/181465.pdf https://www.pewresearch.org/fact-tank/2019/06/12/5-facts-about-illegal-immigration-in-the-u-s/ https://www.pewresearch.org/fact-tank/2019/06/12/5-facts-about-illegal-immigration-in-the-u-s/ https://heinonline.org/HOL/Page?collection=journals&handle=hein.journals/uflr69&id=69&men_tab=srchresults https://heinonline.org/HOL/Page?collection=journals&handle=hein.journals/uflr69&id=69&men_tab=srchresults https://www.reuters.com/article/us-usa-immigration-prisons-exclusive/exclusive-u-s-sending-1600-immigration-detainees-to-federal-prisons-idUSKCN1J32W1 Varghese et al. 733 /us-usa-immigration-prisons-exclusive/exclusive-u-s-sending-1600-immigration -detainees-to-federal-prisons-idUSKCN1J32W1 Lyons, P. M., DeValve, M. J., & Garner, R. L. (2008). Texas police chiefs’ atti- tudes toward gay and lesbian police officers. Police Quarterly, 11, 102–117. doi:10.1177/1098611107302655 Majd, K., Marksamer, J., & Reyes, C. (2009). Hidden injustice: Lesbian, gay, bisexual, and transgender youth in juvenile courts. Retrieved from http://www .nclrights.org/wp-content/uploads/2014/06/hidden_injustice.pdf Maldonado, C. Z., Rodriguez, R. M., Torres, J. R., Flores, Y. S., & Lovato, L. M. (2013). Fear of discovery among Latino immigrants presenting to the emer- gency department. Academic Emergency Medicine, 20, 155–161. doi:10.1111/ acem.12079 Mallory, C., Hasenbush, A., & Sears, B. (2015). Discrimination and harassment by law enforcement officers in the LGBT community. Retrieved from https:// williamsinstitute.law.ucla.edu/wp-content/uploads/LGBT-Discrimination-and -Harassment-in-Law-Enforcement-March-2015.pdf McElvain, J. P., & Kposowa, A. J. (2008). Police officer characteristics and the likelihood of using deadly force. Criminal Justice and Behavior, 35, 505–521. doi:10.1177/0093854807313995 Menjívar, C. (2006). Liminal legality: Salvadoran and Guatemalan immigrants’ lives in the U.S. American Journal of Sociology, 111, 999–1037. doi:10.1086/499509 Menjívar, C., & Perreira, K. M. (2019). Undocumented and unaccompanied: Children of migration in the European Union and the United States. Journal of Ethnic and Migration Studies, 45, 197–217. doi:10.1080/1369183x.2017.1404255 Meyer, I. H. (2003). Prejudice, social stress, and mental health in lesbian, gay, and bisexual populations: Conceptual issues and research evidence. Psychological Bulletin, 129, 674–697. doi:10.1037/0033-2909.129.5.674 Meyer, I. H., Flores, A. R., Stemple, L., Romero, A. P., Wilson, B. M., & Herman, J. L. (2017). Incarceration rates and traits of sexual minorities in the United States: National inmate survey, 2011–2012. American Journal of Public Health, 107, 267–273. doi:10.2105/ajph.2016.303576 Miletick, S. (2019, March 5). Seattle police union official: Reforms deterred offi- cers from seeking out crime, hindered recruitment, retention. The Seattle Times. Retrieved from https://www.seattletimes.com/seattle-news/seattle-police-union -official-reforms-deterred-officers-from-seeking-out-crime-hindered-recruitment -retention/ Miller, T. R., Lawrence, B. A., Carlson, N. N., Hendrie, D., Randall, S., Rockett, I. R., & Spicer, R. S. (2017, February 1). Perils of police action: A cautionary tale from US data sets. Retrieved from https://injuryprevention.bmj.com/content/23/1/27 Moore, R. (2018, May 7). Homeland Security promises to prosecute 100 percent of illegal immigration cases. Retrieved from https://www.texasmonthly.com/news /homeland-security-promises-to-prosecute-100-percent-of-illegal-immigration -cases/ https://www.reuters.com/article/us-usa-immigration-prisons-exclusive/exclusive-u-s-sending-1600-immigration-detainees-to-federal-prisons-idUSKCN1J32W1 https://www.reuters.com/article/us-usa-immigration-prisons-exclusive/exclusive-u-s-sending-1600-immigration-detainees-to-federal-prisons-idUSKCN1J32W1 http://www.nclrights.org/wp-content/uploads/2014/06/hidden_injustice.pdf http://www.nclrights.org/wp-content/uploads/2014/06/hidden_injustice.pdf https://williamsinstitute.law.ucla.edu/wp-content/uploads/LGBT-Discrimination-and-Harassment-in-Law-Enforcement-March-2015.pdf https://williamsinstitute.law.ucla.edu/wp-content/uploads/LGBT-Discrimination-and-Harassment-in-Law-Enforcement-March-2015.pdf https://williamsinstitute.law.ucla.edu/wp-content/uploads/LGBT-Discrimination-and-Harassment-in-Law-Enforcement-March-2015.pdf https://www.seattletimes.com/seattle-news/seattle-police-union-official-reforms-deterred-officers-from-seeking-out-crime-hindered-recruitment-retention/ https://www.seattletimes.com/seattle-news/seattle-police-union-official-reforms-deterred-officers-from-seeking-out-crime-hindered-recruitment-retention/ https://www.seattletimes.com/seattle-news/seattle-police-union-official-reforms-deterred-officers-from-seeking-out-crime-hindered-recruitment-retention/ https://injuryprevention.bmj.com/content/23/1/27 https://www.texasmonthly.com/news/homeland-security-promises-to-prosecute-100-percent-of-illegal-immigration-cases/ https://www.texasmonthly.com/news/homeland-security-promises-to-prosecute-100-percent-of-illegal-immigration-cases/ https://www.texasmonthly.com/news/homeland-security-promises-to-prosecute-100-percent-of-illegal-immigration-cases/ 734 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) Moradi, B., & Grzanka, P. R. (2017). Using intersectionality responsibly: Toward critical epistemology, structural analysis, and social justice activism. Journal of Counseling Psychology, 64, 500–513. doi:10.1037/cou0000203 Nagata, D. K., Kim, J. H. J., & Wu, K. (2019). The Japanese American wartime incarceration: Examining the scope of racial trauma. American Psychologist, 74, 36–48. doi:10.1037/amp0000303 National Center for Transgender Equality. (2018). Policies to increase safety and respect for transgender prisoners: A guide for agencies and advocates. Retrieved from https://transequality.org/safetyfortransprisoners National Conference of State Legislatures (2018). Self-defense and “Stand Your Ground.” Retrieved from http://www.ncsl.org/research/civil-and-criminal-justice /self-defense-and-stand-your-ground.aspx National Immigrant Justice Center (2013). Fact sheet: Children detained by the Department of Homeland Security in adult detention facilities. Retrieved from https://www.immigrantjustice.org/sites/immigrantjustice.org/files/NIJC%20 Fact%20Sheet%20Minors%20in%20ICE%20Custody%202013%2005%20 30%20FINAL_0.pdf National Institute of Justice. (2011). Police use of force, tasers, and other less-lethal weapons. Retrieved from https://www.ncjrs.gov/pdffiles1/nij/232215.pdf National Organization for Victim Assistance. (2018). Crisis response program. Retrieved from https://www.trynova.org/crisis-response-program/ National Prison Rape Elimination Commission. (2009). National prison rape elimina- tion commission report. Retrieved from https://www.ncjrs.gov/pdffiles1/226680 .pdf O’Connor, A. J., & Jahan, F. (2014). Under surveillance and overwrought: American Muslims’ emotional and behavioral responses to government surveillance. Journal of Muslim Mental Health, 8(1), 95–106. doi:10.3998/jmmh.10381607.0008.106 Office of the Inspector General, U.S. Department of Justice (2016, August). Review of the Federal Bureau of Prisons’ monitoring of contract prisons. Retrieved from https://oig.justice.gov/reports/2016/e1606.pdf Olivas, M. A., & Jones, D. Y. (2017). Restoring Pell Grants to prisoners—Growing momentum for reform. Retrieved from https://www.law.uh.edu/ihelg/monograph /17-03.pdf Onyeka-Crawford, A., Patrick, K., & Chaudhry, N. (2017). Let her learn: Stopping school pushout for Girls of Color. National Women’s Law Center. Retrieved from https://nwlc.org/wp-content/uploads/2017/04/final_nwlc_Gates_GirlsofColor .pdf Pager, D. (2003). The mark of a criminal record. American Journal of Sociology, 108, 937–975. doi:10.1086/374403 Pascoe, E. A., & Richman, L. S. (2009). Perceived discrimination and health: A meta- analytic review. Psychological Bulletin, 135, 531–554. doi:10.1037/a0016059. supp Patel v. City of Madison, Alabama, and Eric Sloan Parker, No. 5:15-CV-0253-VEH (N.D. Ala. 2019). https://transequality.org/safetyfortransprisoners http://www.ncsl.org/research/civil-and-criminal-justice/self-defense-and-stand-your-ground.aspx http://www.ncsl.org/research/civil-and-criminal-justice/self-defense-and-stand-your-ground.aspx https://www.immigrantjustice.org/sites/immigrantjustice.org/files/NIJC%20Fact%20Sheet%20Minors%20in%20ICE%20Custody%202013%2005%2030%20FINAL_0.pdf https://www.immigrantjustice.org/sites/immigrantjustice.org/files/NIJC%20Fact%20Sheet%20Minors%20in%20ICE%20Custody%202013%2005%2030%20FINAL_0.pdf https://www.immigrantjustice.org/sites/immigrantjustice.org/files/NIJC%20Fact%20Sheet%20Minors%20in%20ICE%20Custody%202013%2005%2030%20FINAL_0.pdf https://www.ncjrs.gov/pdffiles1/nij/232215.pdf https://www.trynova.org/crisis-response-program/ https://www.ncjrs.gov/pdffiles1/226680.pdf https://www.ncjrs.gov/pdffiles1/226680.pdf https://oig.justice.gov/reports/2016/e1606.pdf https://www.law.uh.edu/ihelg/monograph/17-03.pdf https://www.law.uh.edu/ihelg/monograph/17-03.pdf https://nwlc.org/wp-content/uploads/2017/04/final_nwlc_Gates_GirlsofColor.pdf https://nwlc.org/wp-content/uploads/2017/04/final_nwlc_Gates_GirlsofColor.pdf Varghese et al. 735 Perry, D. M., & Carter-Long, L. (2016). The Ruderman White paper on media cov- erage of law enforcement use of force and disability: A media study (2013– 2015) and overview. Retrieved from http://rudermanfoundation.org/wp-content /uploads/2017/08/MediaStudy-PoliceDisability_final-final.pdf Pew Center on the States. (2009). One in 31: The long reach of American correc- tions. Retrieved from https://www.pewtrusts.org/~/media/assets/2009/03/02 /pspp_1in31_report_final_web_32609.pdf Pham, H. (2018). 287(g) agreements in the Trump Era. Washington & Lee Law Review, 75, 1253–1286. Retrieved from https://scholarlycommons.law.wlu.edu /cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=4609&context=wlulr Piquero, A. R., & Jennings, W. G. (2016). Research note: Justice system-imposed financial penalties increase the likelihood of recidivism in a sample of ado- lescent offenders. Youth Violence and Juvenile Justice, 15, 325–340. doi:10. 1177/1541204016669213 Polaris Project. (2013). Human trafficking trends in the U.S. National Human Trafficking Resource Center 2007–2012. Retrieved from https://polarisproject .org/resources/human-trafficking-trends-2007-2012 Police Executive Research Forum (2015). Re-engineering training on police use of force. Critical issues in policing series. Retrieved from http://www.policeforum .org/assets/reengineeringtraining1.pdf Policing and profit. (2015, April 10). Harvard Law Review, 128, 1723–1746. Retrieved from https://harvardlawreview.org/2015/04/policing-and-profit/ Poteat, V. P., Scheer, J. R., & Chong, E. S. K. (2016). Sexual orientation-based dis- parities in school and juvenile justice discipline: A multiple group comparison of contributing factors. Journal of Educational Psychology, 108(2), 229–241. doi:10.1037/edu0000058 Prison Policy Initiative. (2019, May). Policing women: Race and gender disparities in police stops, searches, and use of force. Retrieved from https://www.prisonpolicy .org/blog/2019/05/14/policingwomen/ Prilleltensky, I. (2014). Justice and human development. International Journal of Educational Psychology, 3, 287–305. doi:10.4471/ijep.2014.15 Pryce, J. (2018, September 13). The long history of separating families in the US and how the trauma lingers. The Conversation. Retrieved from http://theconversation.com/the -long-history-of-separating-families-in-the-us-and-how-the-trauma-lingers-98616 Rampey, B. D., Keiper, S., Mohadjer, L., Krenzke, T., Li, J., Thornton, N., & Hogan, J. (2016). Highlights from the U.S. PIAAC survey of incarcerated adults: Their skills, work experience, education, and training: Program for the International Assessment of Adult Competencies: 2014 (NCES 2016-040). Retrieved from https://nces.ed.gov/pubs2016/2016040.pdf Ramsey, R. (2019, July 1). Analysis: The family separation crisis peaked more than a year ago. Conditions at the border are still terrible. The Texas Tribune. Retrieved from https://www.texastribune.org/2019/07/01/family-separation-crisis-peaked- year-ago-conditions-still-terrible/ http://rudermanfoundation.org/wp-content/uploads/2017/08/MediaStudy-PoliceDisability_final-final.pdf http://rudermanfoundation.org/wp-content/uploads/2017/08/MediaStudy-PoliceDisability_final-final.pdf https://www.pewtrusts.org/~/media/assets/2009/03/02/pspp_1in31_report_final_web_32609.pdf https://www.pewtrusts.org/~/media/assets/2009/03/02/pspp_1in31_report_final_web_32609.pdf https://scholarlycommons.law.wlu.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=4609&context=wlulr https://scholarlycommons.law.wlu.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=4609&context=wlulr https://polarisproject.org/resources/human-trafficking-trends-2007-2012 https://polarisproject.org/resources/human-trafficking-trends-2007-2012 http://www.policeforum.org/assets/reengineeringtraining1.pdf http://www.policeforum.org/assets/reengineeringtraining1.pdf https://harvardlawreview.org/2015/04/policing-and-profit/ https://www.prisonpolicy.org/blog/2019/05/14/policingwomen/ https://www.prisonpolicy.org/blog/2019/05/14/policingwomen/ http://theconversation.com/the-long-history-of-separating-families-in-the-us-and-how-the-trauma-lingers-98616 http://theconversation.com/the-long-history-of-separating-families-in-the-us-and-how-the-trauma-lingers-98616 https://nces.ed.gov/pubs2016/2016040.pdf https://www.texastribune.org/2019/07/01/family-separation-crisis-peaked-year-ago-conditions-still-terrible/ https://www.texastribune.org/2019/07/01/family-separation-crisis-peaked-year-ago-conditions-still-terrible/ 736 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) Raphael, S., & Stoll, M. A. (2013). Assessing the contribution of the deinstitutional- ization of the mentally ill to growth in the U.S. incarceration rate. The Journal of Legal Studies, 42(1), 187–222. doi:10.1086/667773 Reisner, S. L., Bailey, Z., & Sevelius, J. M. (2014). Racial/ethnic disparities in history of incarceration, experiences of victimization, and associated health indicators among transgender women in the U.S. Women & Health, 54, 750–767. doi:10.1 080/03630242.2014.932891 Richards-Ward, L. A., & McDaniel, C. (2007). Corrections in Aotearao/New Zealand: Current issues and future challenges. In R. K. Ax, & T. J. Fagan (Eds.), Corrections, mental health, and social policy: International perspectives. Springfield, IL: Charles Thomas. Robinson, B. A., Winiarski, D. A., Brennan, P. A., Foster, S. L., Cunningham, P. B., & Whitmore, E. A. (2015). Social context, parental monitoring, and multi- systemic therapy outcomes. Psychotherapy, 52, 103–110. doi:10.1037/a0037948 Ross, M. B, Fazzalaro, J., Barone, K., & Kalinowski, J. (2016, May). State of Connecticut: Traffic stop data analysis and findings, 2014–2015. Connecticut Racial Profiling Prohibition Project. Retrieved from https://www.ccsu.edu/imrp /Publicatons/Files/May%202016%20Connecticut%20Racial%20Profiling%20 Report.pdf Roth, M. P. (2005). Crime and punishment: A history of the criminal justice system (1st ed.). Belmont, CA: Cengage. Rothwell, G. R., & Baldwin, J. N. (2007). Whistle-blowing and the code of silence in police agencies: Policy and structural predictors. Crime & Delinquency, 53, 605–632. doi:10.1177/0011128706295048 Ruffin, R. D. (2017). Examining minority perceptions of police behavior (Unpublished dissertation). Retrieved from ProQuest. Saar, M. S., Epstein, R., Rosenthal, L., & Vafa, Y. (2015). The sexual abuse to prison pipeline: The girls’ story. Human Rights Project for Girls. Retrieved from https:// rights4girls.org/wp-content/uploads/r4g/2015/02/2015_COP_sexual-abuse_layout_ web-1.pdf Sikh American Legal Education Defense Fund. (2007, April 12). Sikh American vet- eran assaulted by police officer in Illinois. Retrieved from http://saldef.org/news /sikh-american-veteran-assaulted-by-police-officer-in-illinois/#.W8k9ThNKgy9 Sanghera, J. (2005). Unpacking the trafficking discourse. In K. Kempandoo (Ed.), New perspectives on migration, sex work, and human rights (pp. 3–24). Boulder, CO: Paradigm. Schwartztol, L. (2017). The role of courts in eliminating the racial impact of crimi- nal justice debt. National Center for State Courts. Retrieved from http://www .ncsc.org/~/media/Microsites/Files/Trends%202017/Eliminating-Racial-Impact -Trends-2017.ashx Senate Select Committee on Intelligence. (2014, December 3). Committee study of the Central Intelligence Agency’s Detention and Interrogation Program. United States Senate. Retrieved from https://fas.org/irp/congress/2014_rpt/ssci-rdi.pdf https://www.ccsu.edu/imrp/Publicatons/Files/May%202016%20Connecticut%20Racial%20Profiling%20Report.pdf https://www.ccsu.edu/imrp/Publicatons/Files/May%202016%20Connecticut%20Racial%20Profiling%20Report.pdf https://www.ccsu.edu/imrp/Publicatons/Files/May%202016%20Connecticut%20Racial%20Profiling%20Report.pdf https://rights4girls.org/wp-content/uploads/r4g/2015/02/2015_COP_sexual-abuse_layout_web-1.pdf https://rights4girls.org/wp-content/uploads/r4g/2015/02/2015_COP_sexual-abuse_layout_web-1.pdf https://rights4girls.org/wp-content/uploads/r4g/2015/02/2015_COP_sexual-abuse_layout_web-1.pdf http://saldef.org/news/sikh-american-veteran-assaulted-by-police-officer-in-illinois/#.W8k9ThNKgy9 http://saldef.org/news/sikh-american-veteran-assaulted-by-police-officer-in-illinois/#.W8k9ThNKgy9 http://www.ncsc.org/~/media/Microsites/Files/Trends%202017/Eliminating-Racial-Impact-Trends-2017.ashx http://www.ncsc.org/~/media/Microsites/Files/Trends%202017/Eliminating-Racial-Impact-Trends-2017.ashx http://www.ncsc.org/~/media/Microsites/Files/Trends%202017/Eliminating-Racial-Impact-Trends-2017.ashx https://fas.org/irp/congress/2014_rpt/ssci-rdi.pdf Varghese et al. 737 Shaked-Schroer, N., Costanzo, M., & Marcus-Newhall, A. (2008). Reducing racial bias in the penalty phase of capital trials. Behavioral Sciences & the Law, 26, 603–617. doi:10.1002/bsl.829 Shared Hope International. (2016). Building a legal framework of protection for the nation’s children. Protected Innocence Challenge Toolkit 2016. Retrieved from http://sharedhope.org/wp-content/uploads/2016/11/PIC2016REPORT2.pdf Skaggs, S. (2019). Atypical jobs in psychology: Interview of judge Michael O. Miller. Psychological Services. Advance online publication. doi:10.1037/ser0000377 Solis, C., Portillos, E. L., & Brunson, R. K. (2009). Latino youths’ experiences with and perceptions of involuntary police encounters. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 623(1), 39–51. doi:10.1177/0002716208330487 Stinson, P. M. (2017, May 31). Charging a police officer in fatal shooting case is rare, and a conviction is even rarer. New York Daily News. Retrieved from http:// www.nydailynews.com/newyork/convicting-fatal-shooting-case-rare-event -article-1.3210936 Stumpf, J. (2006). The crimmigration crisis: Immigrants, crime, and sovereign power. American University Law Review, 56, 367–419. Retrieved from http:// digitalcommons.wcl.american.edu/aulr/vol56/iss2/3 Subramanian, R., & Shames, A. (2013). Sentencing and prison practices in Germany and the Netherlands: Implications for the United States. Retrieved from https:// www.prisonpolicy.org/scans/vera/european-american-prison-report-v3.pdf Subramanian, R., Riley, K., & Mai, C. (2018). Divided justice: Trends in Black and White jail incarceration, 1990–2013. Retrieved from http://www.safetyandjusti- cechallenge.org/wp-content/uploads/2018/02/Divided-Justice-full-report.pdf Sun, I. Y., & Wu, Y. (2015). Arab Americans’ confidence in police. Crime & Delinquency, 61, 483–508. doi:10.1177/0011128711420103 Sun, I. Y., Wu, Y., & Poteyeva, M. (2011). Arab Americans’ opinion on counterter- rorism measures: The impact of race, ethnicity, and religion. Studies in Conflict & Terrorism, 34, 540–555. doi:10.1080/1057610X.2011.578550 Swaine, J., & McCarthy, C. (2017, January 8). Young Black men faced highest rates of US police killings in 2016. The Guardian. Retrieved from https://www.theguardian .com/us-news/2017/jan/08/the-counted-police-killings-2016-young-black-men The President’s Task Force on 21st Century Policing. (2015). Final report of the President’s Task Force on 21st Century Policing. Retrieved from https://cops .usdoj.gov/pdf/taskforce/taskforce_finalreport.pdf Thompson, M. (2019). Children at the border: Existing tools for effective advocacy. Law and Contemporary Problems, 82, 217–242. Retrieved from https://lcp.law .duke.edu/article/note-thompson-vol82-iss2/ Toporek, R. L., & Daniels, J. (2018). American Counseling Association Advocacy Competencies-Updated. Retrieved from https://www.counseling.org/docs/default -source/competencies/aca-2018-advocacy-competencies.pdf Tow Youth Justice Institute. (2017). A journey through Connecticut’s juvenile justice system reform. Retrieved from https://www.newhaven.edu/_resources /documents/lee-college/institutes/tow-youth-justice-institute/newsletter/tyji -newsletter-sept-9-26-17.pdf http://sharedhope.org/wp-content/uploads/2016/11/PIC2016REPORT2.pdf http://www.nydailynews.com/newyork/convicting-fatal-shooting-case-rare-event-article-1.3210936 http://www.nydailynews.com/newyork/convicting-fatal-shooting-case-rare-event-article-1.3210936 http://www.nydailynews.com/newyork/convicting-fatal-shooting-case-rare-event-article-1.3210936 http://digitalcommons.wcl.american.edu/aulr/vol56/iss2/3 http://digitalcommons.wcl.american.edu/aulr/vol56/iss2/3 https://www.prisonpolicy.org/scans/vera/european-american-prison-report-v3.pdf https://www.prisonpolicy.org/scans/vera/european-american-prison-report-v3.pdf http://www.safetyandjusticechallenge.org/wp-content/uploads/2018/02/Divided-Justice-full-report.pdf http://www.safetyandjusticechallenge.org/wp-content/uploads/2018/02/Divided-Justice-full-report.pdf https://www.theguardian.com/us-news/2017/jan/08/the-counted-police-killings-2016-young-black-men https://www.theguardian.com/us-news/2017/jan/08/the-counted-police-killings-2016-young-black-men https://cops.usdoj.gov/pdf/taskforce/taskforce_finalreport.pdf https://cops.usdoj.gov/pdf/taskforce/taskforce_finalreport.pdf https://lcp.law.duke.edu/article/note-thompson-vol82-iss2/ https://lcp.law.duke.edu/article/note-thompson-vol82-iss2/ https://www.counseling.org/docs/default-source/competencies/aca-2018-advocacy-competencies.pdf https://www.counseling.org/docs/default-source/competencies/aca-2018-advocacy-competencies.pdf https://www.newhaven.edu/_resources/documents/lee-college/institutes/tow-youth-justice-institute/newsletter/tyji-newsletter-sept-9-26-17.pdf https://www.newhaven.edu/_resources/documents/lee-college/institutes/tow-youth-justice-institute/newsletter/tyji-newsletter-sept-9-26-17.pdf https://www.newhaven.edu/_resources/documents/lee-college/institutes/tow-youth-justice-institute/newsletter/tyji-newsletter-sept-9-26-17.pdf 738 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) Treatment Advocacy Center. (2015). Overlooked in the undercounted. Retrieved from http://www.treatmentadvocacycenter.org/overlooked-in-the-undercounted Trump, President of the United States v. Hawaii Court of Appeals, No. 17–965 (9th Cir. 2018). University of Central Arkansas. (2018). UCA partners with middle school to provide school psychology services. UCA News. Retrieved from http://uca.edu/news/uca -partners-with-middle-school-to-provide-school-psychology-services/ U.S. Census Bureau. (2017, July 1). Quick facts. Retrieved from https://www.census .gov/quickfacts/fact/table/US/PST045217#PST045217 U.S. Citizenship and Immigration Services. (2014). INS records for 1930s Mexican repatriations. United States Department of Homeland Security. Retrieved from https://www.uscis.gov/history-and-genealogy/our-history/historians-mailbox /ins-records-1930s-mexican-repatriations U.S. Customs and Border Protection. (2016, October 18). Southwest border unaccom- panied alien children statistics FY 2016. Retrieved from https://www.cbp.gov /newsroom/stats/southwest-border-unaccompanied-children/fy-2016 U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. (2017, August). Mental health myths and facts. Retrieved from https://www.mentalhealth.gov/basics/mental-health -myths-facts U.S. Department of Justice. (2013). Immigration offenders in the Federal Justice System, 2010. Retrieved from https://www.bjs.gov/content/pub/pdf/iofjs10.pdf U.S. Department of Justice, Civil Rights Division. (2015). Investigation of the Ferguson Police Department. Retrieved from https://www.justice.gov/sites /default/files/opa/press-releases/attachments/2015/03/04/ferguson_police_ department_report.pdf U.S. Department of Justice, Federal Bureau of Prisons. (2018). Transgender offender manual (Publication No. 5200.04 CN-1). Retrieved from https://www.bop.gov /policy/progstat/5200-04-cn-1.pdf U.S. Department of State. (2018, June). Trafficking of person report. Retrieved from https://www.state.gov/wp-content/uploads/2019/06/2019-Trafficking-in-Persons -Report.pdf U.S. Sentencing Commission (2016). Recidivism among federal offenders: A com- prehensive overview. Retrieved from https://www.ussc.gov/sites/default/files/pdf /research-and-publications/research-publications/2016/recidivism_overview.pdf U.S. Sentencing Commission. (2017a). Demographic differences in sentencing: An update to the 2012 booker report. Retrieved from https://www.ussc.gov/sites /default/files/pdf/research-and-publications/research-publications/2017 /20171114_Demographics.pdf U.S. Sentencing Commission. (2017b). Overview of mandatory minimum penalties in the federal criminal justice system. Retrieved from https://www.ussc.gov/sites /default/files/pdf/research-and-publications/research-publications/2017 /20170711_Mand-Min-Figures.pdf United States v. City of Cleveland, No. 1:15 CV 1046 (N.D. Ohio 2015). United States v. City of Ferguson Eastern District of Missouri, Case 4:16 CV00180 (2016). http://www.treatmentadvocacycenter.org/overlooked-in-the-undercounted http://uca.edu/news/uca-partners-with-middle-school-to-provide-school-psychology-services/ http://uca.edu/news/uca-partners-with-middle-school-to-provide-school-psychology-services/ https://www.census.gov/quickfacts/fact/table/US/PST045217#PST045217 https://www.census.gov/quickfacts/fact/table/US/PST045217#PST045217 https://www.uscis.gov/history-and-genealogy/our-history/historians-mailbox/ins-records-1930s-mexican-repatriations https://www.uscis.gov/history-and-genealogy/our-history/historians-mailbox/ins-records-1930s-mexican-repatriations https://www.cbp.gov/newsroom/stats/southwest-border-unaccompanied-children/fy-2016 https://www.cbp.gov/newsroom/stats/southwest-border-unaccompanied-children/fy-2016 https://www.mentalhealth.gov/basics/mental-health-myths-facts https://www.mentalhealth.gov/basics/mental-health-myths-facts https://www.bjs.gov/content/pub/pdf/iofjs10.pdf https://www.justice.gov/sites/default/files/opa/press-releases/attachments/2015/03/04/ferguson_police_department_report.pdf https://www.justice.gov/sites/default/files/opa/press-releases/attachments/2015/03/04/ferguson_police_department_report.pdf https://www.justice.gov/sites/default/files/opa/press-releases/attachments/2015/03/04/ferguson_police_department_report.pdf https://www.bop.gov/policy/progstat/5200-04-cn-1.pdf https://www.bop.gov/policy/progstat/5200-04-cn-1.pdf https://www.state.gov/wp-content/uploads/2019/06/2019-Trafficking-in-Persons-Report.pdf https://www.state.gov/wp-content/uploads/2019/06/2019-Trafficking-in-Persons-Report.pdf https://www.ussc.gov/sites/default/files/pdf/research-and-publications/research-publications/2016/recidivism_overview.pdf https://www.ussc.gov/sites/default/files/pdf/research-and-publications/research-publications/2016/recidivism_overview.pdf https://www.ussc.gov/sites/default/files/pdf/research-and-publications/research-publications/2017/20171114_Demographics.pdf https://www.ussc.gov/sites/default/files/pdf/research-and-publications/research-publications/2017/20171114_Demographics.pdf https://www.ussc.gov/sites/default/files/pdf/research-and-publications/research-publications/2017/20171114_Demographics.pdf https://www.ussc.gov/sites/default/files/pdf/research-and-publications/research-publications/2017/20170711_Mand-Min-Figures.pdf https://www.ussc.gov/sites/default/files/pdf/research-and-publications/research-publications/2017/20170711_Mand-Min-Figures.pdf https://www.ussc.gov/sites/default/files/pdf/research-and-publications/research-publications/2017/20170711_Mand-Min-Figures.pdf Varghese et al. 739 Varghese, F. P., Nolan, J., Bihm, E., Salagame, K. K., Khanna, R., & Ali, S. R. (2017). Transformational leadership and Asian Indian values: Duty, self- less service, and non-violence. The Counseling Psychologist, 45, 810–829. doi:10.1177/0011000017723080 Varghese, F. P., Hardin, E. E., & Bauer, R. L. (2009). Factors influencing the employ- ability of Latinos: The roles of ethnicity, criminal history, and qualifications. Race and Social Problems, 1, 171–181. doi:10.1007/s12552-009-9014-2 Victims of Trafficking and Violence and Protection Act of 2000, Pub. L. 106-386, 114 Stat. 1464, codified as amended at USC §101–113. Walker, S., Spohn, C., & DeLone, M. (2018). The color of justice: Race, ethnicity, and crime in America (6th ed.). Boston, MA: Cengage Learning. Williams, I. (2011). Arizona senate bill 1070: State sanctioned racial profiling? Journal of the Legal Profession, 36, 269–284. Retrieved from https://heinonline .org/HOL/LandingPage?handle=hein.journals/jlegpro36&div=12&id=&page= Wilper, A. P., Woolhandler, S., Boyd, J. W., Lasser, K. E., McCormick, D., Bor, D. H., & Himmelstein, D. U. (2009). The health and health care of US prisoners: Results of a nationwide survey. American Journal of Public Health, 99, 666–672. doi:10.2105/ajph.2008.144279 Wilson, B. D. M., Jordan, S. P., Meyer, I. H., Flores, A. R., Stemple, L., & Herman, J. L. (2017). Disproportionality and disparities among sexual minority youth in cus- tody. Journal of Youth and Adolescence, 46, 1547–1561. doi:10.1007/s10964- 017-0632-5 Wistrich, A. J., & Rachlinski, J. J. (2017). Implicit bias in judicial decision making how it affects judgment and what judges can do about it. In S. Redfield (Ed.), Enhancing justice: Reducing bias (Chapter 5). Retrieved from https://papers .ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2934295 Wright, J. P., Dietrich, K. N., Ris, M. D., Hornung, R. W., Wessel, S. D., Lanphear, B. P., Mona, H., & Rae, M. N. (2008). Association of prenatal and childhood blood lead concentrations with criminal arrests in early adulthood. PLoS Med, 5, 732–740. doi:10.1371/journal.pmed.0050101 Author Biographies Femina P. Varghese, PhD, is an associate professor and the Director of Training of the Counseling Psychology Ph.D. Program at the University of Central Arkansas. She investigates risk and protective factors, particularly the role of work, in recidivism in justice-involved adults and youth. She also studies the effectiveness of telehealth modalities. She is past President of the American Psychological Association Division 18: Psychologists in Public Service and also served as Chair of its Criminal Justice section. Tania Israel, PhD, is a professor of Counseling, Clinical, and School Psychology at the University of California, Santa Barbara. As Director of Project RISE (Research and Interventions for Sexual and Gender Minority Empowerment), she conducts research relevant to scholarship, policy, and practice on interventions to support the https://heinonline.org/HOL/LandingPage?handle=hein.journals/jlegpro36&div=12&id=&page= https://heinonline.org/HOL/LandingPage?handle=hein.journals/jlegpro36&div=12&id=&page= https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2934295 https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2934295 740 The Counseling Psychologist 47(5) mental health and well-being of LGBTQ individuals and communities. Dr. Israel is a fellow of the American Psychological Association and a past President of the Society of Counseling Psychology. Guy Seymour, PhD, is an Afro Caribbean forensic and public safety psychologist in private practice in Decatur, Georgia. The founding director of the Center for Multicultural Training in Psychology at Boston City Hospital and Boston University School of Medicine and the first Chief Psychologist of the Atlanta Police Department, he is a life member both of the American Psychological Association and of the International Association of Chiefs of Police. He has been a member of the National Organization of Black Law Enforcement Executives and of the Association of Black Psychologists and he served as Co-Director of the Crisis Response team for the 1996 Centennial Olympic Games and as Transit Police Crisis Response Coordinator for the 2004 Democratic National Convention. Rachel Becker Herbst, PhD, is an assistant professor in the University of Cincinnati College of Medicine and the lead psychologist over integrated behavioral health ser- vices in pediatric primary care at Cincinnati Children’s Hospital Medical Center. Dr. Herbst provides direct patient care and leads scholarly and advocacy efforts to enhance the capacity of pediatric primary care providers and community partners to provide effective, family-centered health promotion services that address racial, eth- nic, and socio-economic disparities. Lauren G. Suarez, PhD, is a staff psychologist at the Bruce W. Carter VA Medical Center. She oversees the pain psychology program at the Whole Health Center for Pain Management. In addition, she is part of the Posttraumatic Stress Disorder Clinical Team and specializes in military sexual trauma. Dr. Suarez serves as adjunct faculty to the University of Miami School of Education and Human Development. Her areas of clinical and scholarly interest include trauma, holistic health, and social justice. Candice Hargons, PhD, is an assistant professor at the University of Kentucky, where she studies sex, social justice, and leadership, all with a love ethic. She is the founding director of the Center for Healing Racial Trauma. work_hraft23hizcr7eivy5ditwkt6a ---- Family Conferencing in South Australia and Re-offending: Preliminary Results from the SAJJ Project YOUTH JUSTICE CONFERENCING AND RE-OFFENDING* Hennessey Hayes Kathleen Daly School of Criminology and Criminal Justice Griffith University Brisbane, Queensland 4111 Australia Address all correspondence to H Hayes: h.hayes@mailbox.gu.edu.au +61 7 3875 5781 (campus office) +61 7 3314 8594 (home office) + 61 4 00 832 573 (mobile) +61 7 3875 5608 (fax) This document is the manuscript that was submitted to the publisher in February 2003. Please refer to the published version: Hayes, H. and K. Daly (2003) ‘Youth justice conferencing and re-offending.’ Justice Quarterly 20(4): 725-64. * This research was funded in part by a grant from the Australian Research Council (1998- 99). We thank Brigitte Bouhours for research assistance, and Lorraine Mazerolle, Paul Mazerolle and the reviewers for their helpful comments on earlier versions. http://www.griffith.edu.au/school/ccj/kdaly_docs/kdpaper17.pdf 1 YOUTH JUSTICE CONFERENCING AND RE-OFFENDING Abstract The literature on restorative justice and re-offending consists largely of comparative analyses of justice system interventions and re-offending (e.g., comparisons of restorative justice conferencing and court by using experimental designs or by conducting meta-analyses) and suggests small but significant differences or no differences. We take an alternative approach in assessing the impact of restorative justice conferencing on re-offending, using data from the South Australia Juvenile Justice (SAJJ) Conferencing Project and police records. Drawing from conference observations and official police data, we explore the relative importance of conference dynamics and offender characteristics in predicting future offending. We find that in addition to well-known predictors of re-offending, such as previous offending and social marginality, when youthful offenders were observed to be remorseful and when the outcome was reached by genuine consensus, young people were less likely to re-offend. These findings suggest that when attention is focused on the claimed benefits of conferencing in its own right, it is possible to identify those elements of restorative processes that are associated with reductions in crime. The results from the SAJJ researchers' observations were generally confirmed in separate analyses of the coordinators' and police officers' conference observations. The SAJJ observational and interview data also show that of the five groups in the conference process -- coordinators, police officers, young people (offenders), victims, and the SAJJ observers -- the victims were least able to correctly predict a young person's post-conference offending and most likely to wrongly think the young person would re-offend. Despite this, close to 90% of victims recommended the government keep conferencing in the justice system. 2 YOUTH JUSTICE CONFERENCING AND RE-OFFENDING Any new criminal justice practice is confronted by a disarmingly simple question, "does it work"? When asking this question, policymakers and others want to know if a practice reduces re-offending or if it has some constructive impact on those caught up in the criminal justice system. Although criminologists have long recognized that research on crime control, justice practices, and re-offending is beset with conceptual, measurement, and interpretive problems, the politics of criminal justice demands evidence of this sort. A recent criminal justice innovation -- conferencing in the response to youth crime -- has been subject to intensive research, although the focus of most studies has been victims' and offenders' perceptions of what happened in a conference, more so than its longer-term effects such as victim recovery and crime reduction. This is understandable in that conferencing is a recent development, having emerged during the 1990s in New Zealand, Australia, North America, England, among other countries. This paper reviews the theoretical claims and empirical studies of conferencing and re-offending, considers problems of measuring re-offending, and presents new data on conferencing and re-offending from the South Australia Juvenile Justice (SAJJ) project. We focus largely, although not exclusively, on developments in Australia and New Zealand because these countries have utilized conferences longer than any other and within a legislative framework. YOUTH JUSTICE CONFERENCING Youth justice conferencing in Australia followed developments in New Zealand after passage of the Children, Young Persons and their Families Act in 1989. South Australia was the first Australian jurisdiction to establish a legislative basis for conferencing (1993) and to use conferences routinely in youth justice cases (1994). Interest in conferencing grew rapidly in the 1990s (see reviews in Bargen, 1996; Daly, 2001a), and by the end of the decade, all eight Australian states and territories established conferencing, and all but two jurisdictions (Victoria and the ACT) have legislated schemes (Daly & Hayes, 2001). Although there are significant differences in how conferences are organized and administered in Australia and New Zealand1, it is possible to characterize what happens, or 1 Variation in conferencing is greater if we include the police-run model of scripted conferencing, the prevalent model in North America and England (see Young, 2001). In Australia and New Zealand the prevalent model normally has at least two professionals present (a police officer and conference coordinator). 3 ideally, is supposed to happen when it is used as a diversion from court prosecution.2 Upon referral by a police officer or magistrate, a young person who has admitted to an offense, his/her parents or caregivers, the victim and his/her supporters, any other relevant parties to the offense, a police officer and conference facilitator (or coordinator/convenor) come together to discuss the offense. There are three phases in a conference, which normally ranges in length from 60 to 90 minutes: introductory, a discussion of the offense and its impact, and a discussion of the agreement. In the introductory phase, the facilitator introduces the participants and outlines what the aims and ground rules are for the conference, its legal status, and the expected roles and responsibilities of those in the room. Most participants receive this information prior to the conference, during the "intake" process. During the introduction, however, the facilitator emphasizes how the conference will proceed and what the conference should achieve – e.g., that everyone will be given an opportunity to discuss the offense and its impact, as well as negotiate a suitable response to it. In the second phase, the police officer reads an official account of the incident, and the young person (offender) describes what happened, as does the victim(s).3 There is a general discussion of the immediate effect of the offense on the young person, victim, and their supporters; and victims may ask offenders questions such as "Why me?" and "Will this happen to me again?" A typical outcome (although not universal) from the discussion phase is an apology by the offender to the victim. In the third phase, conference participants propose and discuss ways for the young person to "make up for the offense," and particular emphasis is given to negotiating an outcome that is agreeable to everyone in the room. In Queensland, for example, the most common way young offenders "make amends" is to offer a verbal apology. Other outcomes, such as direct restitution, are less common and occur in 2 Conferences are also used to provide pre-sentencing advice to judges and magistrates; currently, this option is utilized more frequently in New Zealand than Australia (see Consedine & Bowen, 1999). 3 The sequence of a police officer's reading of the case information and the offender's version of events varies within and across Australian and New Zealand jurisdictions. Victim presence in conferences also varies: in high-volume jurisdictions such as New Zealand and South Australia, victims are typically present in 50 to 60% of conferences, whereas in low-volume jurisdictions such as Queensland, victims are present in over 90% (Hayes et al. 1998). In South Australia when actual victims do not attend conferences, their views may be given by a family member (especially when victims are young), or they may be represented by a Victim Support Services worker. There is also significant jurisdictional variation in which people, at a minimum, must agree to an outcome. In South Australia, it is only the police officer and young person. See Daly and Hayes (2001) for a review of jurisdictional variation in Australia. 4 only about a quarter of all cases (Hayes, Prenzler & Wortley, 1998).4 During the conference, the facilitator is expected to lead the discussion and ensure that everyone has a chance to speak, and the police officer is expected to provide an authoritative legal presence and to describe the likely effects of future offending for the young person. Both professionals are to ensure that the outcome is appropriate and not excessive. While admitting to the offense (i.e., taking responsibility for wrongdoing) is the primary eligibility criterion for referral to a restorative justice conference, police officers consider other factors when exercising their discretion over how to proceed. In all Australian jurisdictions where conferencing is legislated, police officers should consider the nature of the offense and the young person's prior offending history. There is a broad range of offenses that may be conferenced. In some jurisdictions, conferencing tends to be reserved for less serious crimes (e.g., Western Australia). Other states, such as South Australia, tend to conference more serious crimes, including sexual offenses. Prior offending also is a factor. A conference is viewed as the preferred diversionary option for young offenders with either no prior offenses or only minor offenses on record. However, there remains considerable variation in the type of offenders referred to conference, with some jurisdictions referring serious repeat offenders (Daly & Hayes, 2001). THEORISING CONFERENCING AND RE-OFFENDING There are several ways of theorising the links between conferencing and re-offending, and they can be used in combination. The most developed is Braithwaite's (1989) theory of reintegrative shaming, which he developed before conferencing was introduced in New Zealand and which was originally based on the idea that some societies have more effective methods of social control than others because they "shame reintegratively" in that they "follow shaming ceremonies with ceremonies of repentance and reacceptance" (p. 74). Applying these ideas to conferencing, Braithwaite and Mugford (1994: 142) proposed that (1) an illegal act, not an offending person, should be denounced or "stigmatized" and (2) the people who would be most effective in inducing shame in youthful offenders would be significant others in their lives (for example, a parent or favoured aunt). Following Garfinkel (1956), they depicted contemporary criminal justice practices as status degradation 4 Some critics of restorative justice express concern over the potential for young offenders to receive harsher outcomes rendered by vengeful victims. Common outcomes in Queensland and South Australian conferences, however, would seem to challenge this claim (Hayes et al., 1998; Daly, 2003a). 5 ceremonies, which were about "the sequence disapproval-degradation-exclusion". They argued that reintegration ceremonies, which were about "the sequence disapproval- nondegradation-inclusion" (pp. 142) had a greater capacity to reduce re-offending. This comes about for a variety of reasons, but central among them is that shaming-reintegration ceremonies encourage "law-respecting, other-respecting, and self-respecting" identities in offenders (p. 148, see also, p. 141).5 The concept of reintegrative shaming was first linked to police-run conferencing in Wagga, Wagga, New South Wales in 1991; and it continues to enjoy popularity in police-run conferencing schemes in North America and England (see Young, 2001). Although the concept of reintegrative shaming is thought to be the theory underpinning restorative justice,6 the two should not be conflated. In general, reintegrative shaming focuses on how a conference may affect an offender. Restorative justice assumes a broader set of interactions between an offender and victim (and their supporters) where the recognition of the "other" is expected to encourage a more empathic orientation in the offender and a more sympathetic orientation by the victim to the offender's situation. This distinction is important in understanding the different emphases taken in research on conferencing. In Australia, for example, the Reintegrative Shaming Experiments (RISE) project is testing the theory of reintegrative shaming, but the South Australia Juvenile Justice (SAJJ) project is exploring the dynamics of "restorativeness" between victims, offenders, and their supporters. Both projects are also interested in the degree to which procedural justice features in conferences (RISE and SAJJ are discussed in more detail below). During the 1990s, arguments for the benefits of conference over court in reducing re- offending were augmented with Tyler's (1990) work on procedural justice. There is a good deal of fluidity in how procedural justice is defined and measured, owing to its popularity and applicability to many decision-making sites, the criminal justice system being just one. In brief, Tyler argued that the legal process itself was important to people, independent of its outcome. Indicators of procedurally just processes include suspects (or defendants) stating 5 Since this early work, Braithwaite (1999) developed a more comprehensive set of arguments on the relationship of reintegrative shaming, restorative justice, and crime reduction; and with other colleagues (Ahmed et al. 2001), he revised the theory to better articulate the relationship between the emotion of shame and the practice of shaming. 6 Restorative justice covers a diverse array of practices and organisational contexts. For a review of international debates on definition and variation in practice, see Miers (2001); for a review of its varied strands and antecedents, see Daly and Immarigeon (1998). 6 their case (having voice) and being treated with dignity and respect (standing), and decision- makers viewed as trustworthy and neutral. When legal processes are viewed as procedurally just (in other words, as "fair" and handled by competent and trustworthy authorities), there is an affirmation of the legal order and a commitment to law-abiding behavior. These and related arguments on defiance theory (Sherman, 1993) were taken up in the RISE project. In addition to the psychological dynamics of reintegrative shaming, RISE researchers hypothesized that elements of procedural justice would be more frequent in conferences than in court, and that this, in turn, would encourage even greater law-abiding behavior for conference than court offenders. A variant on the procedural justice and reintegration themes is seen in the development of family group conferencing in New Zealand (Maxwell & Morris, 1993). Growing out of Maori political challenges to the dominant white juvenile and child protection system in the 1980s came the idea that a Maori youth's family group should have greater voice and decision-making control than professionals. The implicit idea behind elevating lay actors over legal authorities or social workers is that a family social group not only had some degree of collective responsibility for the lawbreaker's behavior, it could also render better, perhaps more culturally appropriate decisions. Such decisions, in turn, might dissuade a youth from future offending, not because of his or her belief in the legitimacy of the (white) legal system, but because a family group has taken a more central role in the decision-making process. A final strand has featured for some time in research on reparation, diversion, and restitution schemes in North America, England, and Europe, which include mediated meetings between victims and offenders (see, e.g., Dignan, 1992; Marshall, 1992; Messmer & Otto, 1992; Schneider, 1986; Umbreit & Coates, 1993).7 Several claims are made for the enhanced benefits of alternative (that is, non court or non custody) responses to crime: (1) by diverting offenders from prosecution or from custody, fewer will be subject to the stigmatizing effects of the criminal process (or secondary deviance); (2) when offenders meet the people they victimized, they have a "more powerful reformative experience" (Marshall, 1992: 18); and (3) when offenders are given the chance to make up for their offense by paying money or doing community work, they may "re-establish individual self-esteem" and 7 Some argue against viewing restorative justice as confined to mediation, preferring instead to see it as a "fully- fledged systemic alternative" (Walgrave, 1999: 150). We bypass these and other definitional debates in the interest of broadly sketching the lines of argument in the field. 7 become "socially integrat[ed]" into their local community (Messmer & Otto, 1992: 2-3 ). This strand gives greater attention than the others to the benefits of mediation and negotiation in the justice process. While there is a rich set of claimed benefits of conferencing (or related reparative and mediation schemes of the 1980s and 1990s) over regular court processes, studies to date have mainly focused on participant satisfaction and perceived fairness of the process rather than its impact on re-offending. In fact, some argue that conferencing (or related schemes) were not introduced with the explicit intention of reducing re-offending, but with other aims and outcomes in mind (for example, bringing victims into the justice process, holding offenders accountable, rendering fairer justice and more satisfied participants); thus, they suggest that conferences should be assessed in those terms (see, e.g., Dignan, 1991: 37 on the Kettering scheme in England; Morris & Maxwell, 1997: 4 on family group conferencing in New Zealand). These scholars propose, further, that if the impact of alternative practices shows few or no differences in re-offending compared to a standard court process, this signals success, not failure in using a less intrusive and potentially less stigmatising form of legal intervention. Finally, some point out that while restorative language may exist in legislation setting forth alternatives, when such programs or practices are put into operation, they may be little different than regular court routines (for example, there may be low rates of victim participation, or there may be insufficient resources for adequate preparation and follow through of conference outcomes). Thus, we may expect to see no differences in re-offending (Morris & Gelsthorpe, 2000: 25-29; see also Walgrave, 1999). We review the empirical literature on conferencing and re-offending shortly, but before we do, we consider problems of measuring conferencing and re-offending. MEASURING THE IMPACT OF COURT AND CONFERENING ON RE-OFFENDING Three major problems face researchers in measuring the impact of court and conferencing on re-offending: problems of comparison, differences in when offenders take responsibility for their offending, and other temporal differences. Problems of comparison. In analyzing different types of legal interventions and re- offending, it is uncertain what should be studied or compared. For example, in youth justice, 8 if we compare the effect of court and conference interventions, we overlook other possible legal interventions such as formal cautions or no police action at all. Furthermore, we overlook the potential to investigate a new legal intervention in its own right. If we elect the comparative route, we run into problems of sample selection bias by the police or other officials who may consider some individuals to be "more appropriate" than others for the new alternatives. Although such problems can be addressed with randomized field experiments, these too are not without problems of generalizability. Differences in when offenders take responsibility. A central, if overlooked, problem in the court- conference comparative literature is that conferencing (or other diversion schemes) are available only to those youthful offenders who have admitted to an offense (or in New Zealand, who choose "not to deny"). If we ignore, for the moment, field experimental designs and focus instead on studies of conference and court in natural settings, we find that research on the effects of conferences are of offenders who have decided early on to admit responsibility for an offense. Members of the conference group may well differ from those in a court group in that the latter may not initially admit to the offense, although they may later admit after several court appearances. Therefore, the conference group is already distinctive from the court group in ways that are likely to be theoretically related to re-offending. If, hypothetically, members of the court and conference groups were similar in culpability for their offending, but those in the conference group make an admission at an earlier point in the legal process, we might assume that they have moved further along in a reformation process. This problem may be overcome in field experimental designs (such as the RISE project), where admitted offenders are randomly assigned to court or to a diversionary conference. However, and this is an essential point, to be eligible for random assignment to court or conference, an offender must first admit to the offense. Experiment- eligible offenders who are assigned to court may therefore differ from court offenders who do not admit early on. It is possible that the comparison of admitted court and conference youth in the RISE project partly explains the similarity in rates of re-offending for the two groups for three of the four types of offenses studied (see discussion below). Temporal differences in legal intervention. The temporal differences in taking responsibility for an offense affect the window of time for measuring re-offending. Again, let us focus on studies of conference and court in natural settings, not experimental field designs. Imagine for example, two male offenders who were both equally involved in a burglary early in January. One decides to admit to the offense soon after, and his case is diverted to 9 conference, while the other decides to plead not guilty. Based on data from South Australia, the conference case would likely be disposed of in 6 to 8 weeks, that is, by March; but if the case went to court, it would likely take longer, about 3 to 6 months, perhaps not until April. Let us imagine that the two youths are involved in a second burglary in the middle of March. For the court youth, the offense occurred during the pre-disposition period and would not count as an offense; but for the conference youth, it occurred after the conference and thus would count as an offense. With temporal differences in how conference and court cases are handled in natural settings, there are problems in comparing the two. These may be overcome with using field experimental designs, but as we suggest in the discussion of the RISE project below, this comes at a price of selecting the right start date for counting re- offending. To date, research on conferencing and re-offending has largely been of comparing conferences (or other interventions) with court. While comparative studies have value, they are limited, even with the use of randomised field experiments. We propose that research on re-offending may benefit from a focus on within-intervention variation with the aim of identifying variation in claimed features of the conference process with variation in offending. Scholars have long recognised the many problems of defining and measuring re- offending (Maltz, 1984). Despite these problems, Gendreau, Little and Goggin's (1996) meta-analysis of 131 studies of adult re-offending suggests general patterns. They identified re-offending predictors they termed "static" (the things that cannot be changed) and "dynamic" (the things that can be changed). The strongest static predictors were age/gender/race and criminal history, and the strongest dynamic predictors were "criminogenic need" factors, which they defined as antisocial personality, antisocial companions, interpersonal conflict, antisocial attitudes, and substance abuse (Gendreau et al., 1996: 583-584). Ideally, in analyzing conferencing and re-offending, one would want to determine the predictive power of static factors (age, gender, race, prior offense history) and dynamic factors such as an offender's remorse, positive victim-offender movement, the effect of perceived fairness of treatment, and other features of the conference process that may play a role in modifying an offender's future behavior. 10 RESEARCH ON RESTORATIVE JUSTICE, CONFERENCING, AND RE-OFFENDING Two recurring findings emerge from the literature on conferencing (and restorative justice generally). First, with some exceptions (early work in New Zealand by Maxwell & Morris, 1993), there are generally high levels of satisfaction with the process and outcomes by victims and offenders (Braithwaite, 1999; Daly, 2001a; Kurki, 2001; Marshall, 1999; Miers, Maguire, Goldie, Sharpe, Hale, Netten, Uglow, Doolin, Hallam, Enterkin & Newburn, 2001; Umbreit, Coates & Vos, 2001). Latimer, Dowden and Muise's (2001: 9, 11) meta- analysis of 22 studies found significantly higher levels of satisfaction for victims and offenders who participated in restorative processes compared to regular justice system practices. Satisfaction is a notoriously fuzzy concept with varied referents for victims and offenders, but a common denominator in the restorative justice literature is participants' sense of the fairness of the process and the outcome, and having a say in the decision-making process (van Ness & Schiff, 2001: 50; Umbreit et al., 2001: 131-2). This relates to a second recurring finding, especially in studies of conferencing in Australian states and territories: there are high levels of observed procedural justice (by researchers, police officers, and coordinators sitting in the conference) and perceived procedural justice by victims and offenders (Daly, 2001a). RISE researchers say that higher levels of perceived procedural justice are registered by conference than court offenders (Strang, Barnes, Braithwaite & Sherman, 1999), although Kurki's (2001) review of the RISE data suggests these conclusions are somewhat overdrawn in that court and conference differences vary by offense categories and are not consistently strong. How being "satisfied" with a justice activity or judging it to be "fair" affects offenders is uncertain. Latimer et al.'s (2001: 14) meta-analysis suggests that there are greater reductions in offending for those in "restorative justice programs" compared to others. However, mean effect size for the 32 tests examined was .07 (SD = .13), and effect sizes ranged from -.23 to .32. This seems illustrative of the variability in research findings that compare restorative approaches to conventional "controls" (e.g., Braithwaite, 1999; Dignan, 1991; McCold & Wachtel, 1998; McGarrell, 2001; Miers et al., 2001; Sherman, Strang & Woods, 2000). There are many ways of assessing the effects of restorative programs on re- offending. In this paper, we explore the variable effects of conferencing on re-offending, rather than compare conferencing with other interventions. 11 In Australia and New Zealand, two analytical approaches have been used. One approach, employed in the RISE project, utilises the comparative method in a field experiment design, in which admitted offenders are randomly assigned to court and conference (Sherman et al., 2000). A recent New South Wales study also used the comparative method in a retrospective study of official records (Luke & Lind, 2002). A second approach, employed in New Zealand research by Maxwell and Morris (2001) and in the SAJJ project results presented in this article, analyze variability in the conference process itself, including offenders' orientations to the conference and perceptions of how they were treated, in predicting re-offending. We review the findings from the three studies before turning to the SAJJ project. RISE study in Canberra. The RISE project gathered data on four types of offenses and offenders: drink drivers of all ages, violent offenders up to age 29, juvenile property offenders, and juvenile property offenders having organisational victims (shoplifters). Cases meeting the project criteria (including the offender having admitted to the offense) were randomly assigned to court or conference. The project study site was Canberra (the Australian federal capital), where data were gathered from mid-1995 to mid-2000; the Canberra conferencing model is police-run (see Strang et al., 1999). Sherman et al. (2000) report that for one group of offenders, those charged with violent offenses, there was a significant reduction in the average rate of offending in the post-referral period, compared to those who went to court. However, there were no significant court-conference differences in rates of re-offending for the drink driving, property, and shoplifting offenders. We note several problems with the RISE findings. One, discussed above and which features generally in randomized field experiments, is that members of the court and conference groups are similar in ways that are theoretically related to re-offending: they admitted to an offense early on. A second problem is that the observational window in measuring re-offending is 12 months after an offender was referred to court or a conference. In other words, the RISE findings are of the effects of referral to court or conference, not of the effect of the court or conference itself. The time between referral and intervention ranges from about 2 to 4 months, depending on the type of offense and site of disposition (Sherman 12 et al., 2000: 10, footnote 2).8 While the authors give good measurement reasons for this choice, this rationale comes at the price of making a sensible interpretation of the impact of court or conference on an offender's rate of re-offending. Specifically, during the 2- to 4- month window of time, an offender who was assigned to a conference may have offended several times, then attended the conference, and then not re-offended afterwards. The RISE recidivism study would count this conference a "failure" (in re-offending terms) when it was a success. It is essential, we think, to know the rates of offending for those offenders assigned to a court or conference, after they actually attended court or a conference. New South Wales study. Luke and Lind (2002) compared the effects of diversionary conferencing and youth court on re-offending in the Australian state of New South Wales. To control for the effects of prior record, they gathered official data (available up to 30 June 2001) only for first-time offenders (defined as having no prior proven court case), who appeared in the youth court for 12 months preceding (N = 5,516) and following (N = 3,830) the introduction of conferencing on 6 April 1998. They then gathered data only for first-time offenders, who were conferenced during the first 12 months of the diversionary scheme (6 April 1998 to 5 April 1999; N = 590). Several comparisons were made to separate selection effects from "treatment" effects. The results showed that the conference group had a predicted risk of re-offending and rate of re-appearance approximately 15-20% lower than the two court groups, after controlling for the effects of gender, age, offense type, Aboriginality. From these findings, they surmise that the conference experience had a crime reduction effect. New Zealand study. Maxwell and Morris' (2001) model of re-offending includes an offender's early life experiences, features of the conference itself, and post-conference life experiences. They conducted interviews with 108 young people (and their parents), who had taken part in conferences in New Zealand in 1990-91. (Conferences in New Zealand, like those in most Australian jurisdictions, are not run by the police, but by a facilitator with a police officer present.) The interviews were conducted during 1996-97, about 6 ½ years after the conference, and they focused on childhood experiences in school and families, and the offender's and their parent's recollection of what happened in the conference. Data on 8 For three of the four offense types, the time between referral and legal intervention was shorter for the court group than the conference group, a result that reflects RISE-eligible offenders having to admit the offense early on, coupled with the police officers being slow in organizing RISE conferences (Heather Strang 2002, personal communication). 13 reconvictions during the 6 ½ year period for the 108 youth were obtained from police records; these were organized into four categories, ranging from "not reconvicted" (29% of the sample) to "persistent reconvicted" (28%). The authors found that both early life experiences (e.g., poverty and parental neglect) and events after the family conference (e.g., access to training and employment, exposure to criminal associates) had a significant relationship to re-offending, especially for the persistent reconvicted group. However, they also found several conference factors that were related to reductions in re-offending. These included the young person's feeling remorseful, not being made to feel a bad person, feeling involved in the conference decision-making, agreeing with the conference outcome, and meeting the victim and apologising to him or her (Maxwell & Morris, 2001: 253). They argue that while early childhood interventions are likely to prove more effective than justice system interventions, "family group conferences can moderate the patterns of the past and can contribute to the prevention of offending" (p. 260). One potential problem with this study is that the interviews with the original sample of offenders (and their families) were conducted many years after the conference took place. THE SAJJ PROJECT, CONFERENCING, AND RE-OFFENDING In assessing the impact of conferences on re-offending, we asked whether observed behaviors or outcomes in conferences could predict re-offending, over and above those factors that are known to be highly predictive, such as a person's previous offending and social marginality. We approached the problem of predicting re-offending with the assumption that conferences are variable events, with varying degrees of procedural justice and restorativeness. Our approach is similar to Maxwell and Morris in that we are interested in explaining variability in re-offending from variability in the conference process, rather than comparing the different effects of court or conference on re-offending. Our approach differs, however, in that we utilise observational data gathered by SAJJ researchers at the time of the conference, rather than participants' memories of what occurred many years later. The SAJJ project had two waves of data collection in 1998 and 1999 (see Daly Venables, McKenna, Mumford & Johnston, 1998; Daly, 2001a for detailed reviews of the project's methodology, the instruments used, and the theoretical and research justification for item construction). In 1998, SAJJ researchers observed 89 conferences held in the metropolitan area of Adelaide, South Australia, and in several country towns. The observed conferences were selected on the basis of the offense category. SAJJ-eligible offenses were 14 personal crimes of violence and property offenses that involved personal victims or "community victims" (such as schools, churches, or housing trusts). Excluded were shoplifting cases, drug cases, and public order offenses. With 15% of conferences having multiple offenders, the conferences had 107 distinct offenders. The SAJJ researchers conducted in-depth interviews with offenders and victims in 1998, and again in 1999, one year later.9 For each conference, the police officer and the coordinator completed a self- administered survey, and a SAJJ researcher completed a detailed observational instrument. The SAJJ observational survey and the coordinator and police officer surveys contained many detailed items on what occurred in the conference (in particular, a variety of measures of procedural justice and restorativeness), global judgments of how well the conference went and how well it was managed, the professional relationships between the coordinator and police officer, the emotions expressed in the conference, and who was involved in fashioning the agreement and how it was decided. In this paper, we use the SAJJ observational data in analyzing re-offending; the police and coordinator observational data as a confirmatory analysis of the SAJJ observations; and the SAJJ researcher, police, coordinator, offender, and victim survey and interview data to compare predictions of re-offending. SAJJ observational data were keyed to primary offenders; therefore, the following analysis of re-offending is limited to the 89 primary offenders in the conferences. All independent variables are listed and defined in Table 2. These variables were selected from the SAJJ observational instrument and measure offender, offense, and conference characteristics, as well as restorativeness and procedural justice. Defining and measuring "restorativeness" and "procedural justice". The SAJJ observational instrument gathered detailed information from SAJJ researchers about the conference. The theory of restorative justice suggests that offenders and victims who meet to discuss offending and victimization and to negotiate outcomes will be "restored" by a fair and equitable process. SAJJ observers recorded who attended the conference, how it was managed, and how participants related to one another. Focusing their attention on young offenders and their relationships with other people in the room, observers noted several features of the conference that were indicative of restoration and procedural fairness. "Restorativeness" was measured by observing how young people behaved during the 9 Of the total of 107 young people and 89 primary victims (N = 196), SAJJ researchers interviewed 88% in Year 1; of that group, 94% were again interviewed in Year 2 (see Daly, 2001b for details on and analysis of interview 15 conference – i.e., whether they were defiant or remorseful, took responsibility for their actions, understood the impact of their offending, gave a clear story of the offence, were actively involved in the conference discussion, offered an apology, or assured the victim the offence would not happen again. They also observed how effective victims were at describing the impact of offending, whether victims understood offenders' situations, how the conference ended (e.g., "on a high"), and if there was "positive movement" or shared understandings between offenders and victims. "Procedural justice" was measured by observing how the conference was managed – whether participants treated one another respectfully, if the coordinator permitted everyone to "have a say", if the coordinator seemed impartial, if the coordinator negotiated the outcome well, if the offender appeared "powerless", if the offender understood the relationship between the offence and the outcome, or if the outcome was decided by "genuine consensus". These items were coded 1 when restorative and procedural justice elements were observed to a large degree (e.g., "mostly or fully") and 0 when these elements were observed to be less evident (e.g., "somewhat or not at all"; see Table 3). A striking finding from the SAJJ project is that the members of all five groups -- the SAJJ observer, police officer, coordinator, offender, and victim -- report very high levels of observed or perceived procedural justice. SAJJ observers, police officers, and coordinators rated conferences highly on all the measures of procedural justice. In the face-to-face interviews with offenders and victims after the conference (median time, 25 to 33 days), their response to items such as, "were you treated fairly," "were you treated with respect," "did you have a say in the agreement," among others, registered high levels of procedural justice, with 80 to 95% of victims and offenders saying they were treated fairly and had a say. However, compared to the high levels of observed and perceived procedural justice, there was a relatively lesser degree of "restorativeness" observed in the conference by the SAJJ researchers, police officers, and coordinators, or perceived by offenders and victims when asked in the interviews. These and other SAJJ results are discussed elsewhere (Daly, 2001b, 2002, 2003a), but we note them here to provide some context for the re-offending analysis. Defining and measuring re-offending. We chose to define re-offending operationally as any new official incident (which might involve multiple charges or counts), to which the police responded by arrest or apprehension, after the date of the SAJJ conference. These response rates). Of the 79 victims interviewed in 1998, 61 attended the conference and 18 did not. We refer to the former as the "conference victims" in this article. 16 incidents were dealt with by formal caution, conference, or court. Cases pending, but not finalized in court were included. Included were all violent offenses, property offenses, and driving offenses (normally these were drink driving). Excluded were breaches of good behavior bonds, which related to a previous sentence (or undertaking), because these did not reflect a fresh incident. An official incident can have multiple charges, but our count of pre- and post-conference incidents was of distinct incidents (that is, separated by several weeks or a month). We obtained data from the South Australian police on the type of offense, police actions taken (for example, formal caution, referral to family conference or to court), date of disposition, and outcomes (e.g., conference agreement and court sentence) for the total number of young people in the sample (N = 107) as of 21 March 1999.10 The post- conference window of time is thus 8 to 12 months.11 To operationalize offending, we chose to analyze participation, not incidence. We did so for statistical and theoretical reasons. In preliminary analyses of the effect of several key independent variables on the number of incidents post-conference, the correlation matrix showed that some key variables would have been too highly correlated if we used incidence as the dependent variable. Our theoretical rationale is two-fold. First, our analytic focus is on variation within conferences rather than differences between conferences and some other justice intervention. The latter approach is typically concerned with learning how two interventions affect real or estimated levels of offending (or incidence). We are asking instead: what are the variable effects, if any, of restorative justice conferences on re- offending behavior? Thus, our approach is concerned with learning if offender and conference characteristics are associated with any future involvement in crime (or participation). Second, we are interested to shed light on how a new criminal justice intervention affects the number of offenders in a community (that is, participation), rather than the number of criminal events in a community (that is, incidence; see Sherman et al., 10 Our thanks to Senior Sergeant Dave Wardrop for his assistance with the data collection, as well as his cooperation and counsel in helping us to decode the categories and meanings in official criminal histories. 11 The 89 conferences were sampled during a 4-month period, March through June 1998, the first conference observed was on 9 March and the last, on 25 June 1998. While the 8- to 12-month measurement window is somewhat small, it is wide enough to assess the potential impact of conferencing on re-offending. In fact, an analysis of days to first post-conference official incident showed that 50% of those who re-offended 8-12 months post-conference did so within 3 months (90.5 days), and 93% re-offended within 8 months (240 days). So, while this disparate follow-up period may pose a methodological challenge, this outcome is consistent with what other researchers have observed, that is, if re-offending is going to occur, it will happen shortly following an intervention (Maxwell & Morris, 2001: 245). 17 2000). For some datasets and research purposes, incidence may be the more appropriate dependent variable. For this dataset, an analysis of participation was the more sound approach statistically; and at this stage of investigating the effects of conferences on individual offenders, participation is the better measure. We note that with the exception of Maxwell and Morris (2001), no study has yet attempted to relate measures of what occurred in a conference to re-offending. Previous research has simply compared re-offending rates for court and conference groups, and researchers have only speculated on the reasons for the differences (if any) in re-offending for each group. Offending and re-offending in the SAJJ sample. Unless noted otherwise, our depiction of offenders is of the 89 primary offenders in the conferences, not the total of 107. The reason is that in recording conference observations, SAJJ researchers focused on the behavior and interactions of one designated primary offender when there were multiple offenders, as did the coordinators and police officers. For pre-conference activity, 43% of the young people had not had any official contact prior to the incident that led to the SAJJ conference; thus 43% were "first time" offenders.12 Some 27% had had one contact, and 30% had two or more contacts. For post-conference offending, 60% had no official contact following the conference, 17% had one contact only, and 23% had two or more contacts. The number of pre- and post-conference incidents ranged from none (except the SAJJ incident) to 17. One-third of the sample can be termed "experimenters" in that the SAJJ offense was their only offense; an additional 26% did not re-offend post-conference (we refer to this group as the "desisters").13 The "drifters", those with only post-conference offenses, represent only 9% of young offenders.14 Close to one-third are "persisters," who offended both pre- and post-conference. These proportions are summarized in Table 1. 12 The window of time for pre-conference offending could range from several months to 7 years, depending on the youth's age and how long they have lived in South Australia. In an analysis of the first address shown on the police file, over 80% had come to police attention in the previous 2 years. 13 We appreciate that the term "desister" may connote a fixed state when recent research suggests it is better understood as a temporal process (Laub & Sampson, 2001; Bushway, Piquero, Briody, Cauffman & Mazerolle, 2001). 14 We borrowed this term from the theoretical literature on delinquency to capture the notion of moral release (Matza, 1964). 18 Conferencing and re-offending: bivariate relationships We began by running a series of cross-tabulations between a participation measure of re-offending (our dependent variable, where 1 = re-offended post-conference), offender characteristics, and actions or behaviors occurring in conferences that may be linked to re- offending. Table 2 presents the independent variables in five groups: offender-related, offense-related, conference-related, measures of restorativeness, and measures of procedural justice.15 Phi coefficients were used to assess the strength of the association, and the asterisks indicate the level of statistical significance.16 Measures of restorativeness and procedural justice analyzed here are derived from the SAJJ observational data and do not represent how offenders perceived these features of the conference. For the offender-related variables, males comprise 76% of the sample, and Aboriginal youth, 12%.17 Our measure of social marginality (or residential instability) is the number of distinct residential addresses on file with the South Australian police; nearly 30% of the young people had lived at different addresses three or more times.18 From Table 2 one sees significant bivariate associations for re-offending and Aboriginality, social marginality, and prior offending. Some 64% of Aboriginal youth re-offended, whereas 37% of non- Aboriginal youth did; 72% of residentially unstable youth re-offended compared to 28% of more stable youth; and 55% of those who offended pre-conference re-offended compared with 21% with no prior offending. In light of previous research, we were initially puzzled by an apparent lack of association between sex and re-offending. When we examined sex and race together by crosstabulating a combined sex/race variable with re-offending, we found that re-offending was highest (and similar) for Aboriginal male and female youth (63% and 67%, respectively), 15 It was difficult to classify some measures. For example, "offender was defiant" can be a negative indicator of restorativeness (denying the harm to a victim) or an indicator of procedural justice (reacting against perceptions of being treated unfairly by a legal authority). 16 We concur with Sherman et al. (2000) on the interpretation of statistical significance. While it is conventional to regard effects at the .05 level as statistically significant, a more generous error level of .15 may be appropriate in the policy context. We have limited our interpretation of the bivariate and multivariate analyses to the .10 level. However, we would point out that the phi coefficients of .15 to .16 near statistical significance at the .10 level. 17 SAJJ sample demographics are nearly identical to those of all youth conferenced in 1998 (see Daly, 2001b: 22). 19 followed by non-Aboriginal males (40%), and non-Aboriginal females (28%). From this result, coupled with the low number of Aboriginal females in the sample, it was essential that our multivariate analysis use a set of combined, rather than separated sex and race variables, so we created a set of dummy variables for sex/race. The dummy variables were coded as follows: 1 for Aboriginal male or female, 0 otherwise; 1 for non-Aboriginal male, 0 otherwise. Non-Aboriginal female was the redundant category. For the offense-related variables, Table 2 shows no statistically significant association between re-offending and the type of offense (violent or property) or type of victim (individual or organization, although this neared significance), but does for victim-offender relationships. Those offenders who committed a SAJJ offense against someone they knew were less likely to re-offend. For the conference-related variables, victims were present in 74% of conferences, with an additional 6% attended by a representative of the Victim Support Services. The results show that conferences are calm events with low degrees of anger (10%) and moderate levels of crying (25%). There is no association between re-offending and whether a victim (or professional victim representative) was at the conference, and none for the presence of emotions displayed at the conference. The finding for victim presence is noteworthy in the light of criticisms levelled at conferencing schemes with low rates of victim participation (for example, in New Zealand), which commentators have assumed would result in diminished positive effects. SAJJ researchers judged 10% of conferences to be a "waste of time"; a significantly higher share of young people in such conferences re-offended 8 to 12 months later. The "waste of time" variable is a global measure that captures observers' overall impressions of conference success. Of the nine conferences judged as a waste of time, other observational variables show that for these conferences, the offenders were not at all remorseful, there was little or no positive movement between offenders and victims, and offenders did not understand the impact of the crime on the victim. In one conference involving two young men, the victim was particularly vindictive and lied about the extent of the harm. While these conferences may have been procedurally fair, they lacked elements of mutual understanding between the victim and offender. 18 The number of addresses in the police files did not match the number of arrests on record. In 49% of cases, there were more addresses than arrests on file because address information is recorded when any matter comes to police attention, including victimization, being a witness, and child protection matters. In 33% of cases there were fewer addresses than arrests and in 18% there were equal addresses and arrests on file. 20 Some measures of restorativeness are related to re-offending, and others not. (Note that phi coefficients may be identical in magnitude for some variables, but significant for one and not the other because the number of conferences is smaller for some variables, that is, those involving victims who were present at the conference.) When young people were observed to be remorseful and when SAJJ observers recorded the conference as having ended on a high, a positive note of repair and good will, youth in those conferences were less likely to re-offend. There is no association, however, between re-offending and an offender understanding the impact of the crime on the victim, or a victim being effective in describing the impact of the offense. Based on the expectations of restorative justice theory, we would have expected to see a stronger relationship of re-offending and variables tapping "movement and mutual understanding" between victims, offenders, and their supporters, but this did not emerge. Several measures of restorativeness neared statistical significance at the .10 level: when offenders took responsibility for the offense, were actively involved, and were not defiant, they were less likely to re-offend. For procedural justice, there are no significant associations for what we might term the standard or Tyler-based measures of procedural justice (such as the police officer treating the offender with respect, the coordinator permitting everyone to have a say, the coordinator being impartial, process of deciding outcome was fair) mainly because they had too little variability (ranging from 89 to 99%).19 This is an important finding. Standard measures of procedural justice may be better able to distinguish court and conference processes than they can variability among conferences. One conference-specific procedural justice measure is linked to re-offending. When the outcome was observed to be decided by genuine consensus, young people in those conferences were less likely to re-offend. Conferencing and re-offending: multivariate analyses These bivariate results helped us to identify the variables for our multivariate analyses. We used logistic regression to analyze the effects of offender-related, offense- related and conference-related characteristics, along with measures of restorativeness and procedural justice, on our measure of re-offending. We were interested to determine if, in addition to those offender-related variables known to be predictive of re-offending (not only 19 For example, SAJJ observers recorded the following: police officers treated the young person with respect (99% yes), the young person treated the police officer with respect (96% yes), the coordinator permitted everyone to have a say (98% yes), and the coordinator seemed impartial (93% yes). 21 from the literature, but also from our bivariate analysis of the data), other conference-related variables were predictive. We explored many combinations of variables, although we were limited by the number of variables we could include in the equation because of the number of cases. Table 3 shows the fruits of our analyses. We estimated two models: (1) a full model, which has the variables known to be predictive of re-offending (prior offending, sex/race- ethnicity, social marginality -- our control variables), together with key conference variables; and (2) a reduced model, which included only the controls. Examining the full model, we find that all but one of the control variables were significantly associated with re-offending. Non-Aboriginal males were more likely to re-offend, as were residentially unstable youth and those with pre-conference offending. Over and above these offender characteristics, there were two significant conference variables. When young people were observed to be remorseful and when they participated in conferences in which outcomes were decided by genuine consensus, they were less likely to re-offend. Overall, 80% of cases were correctly classified with this model, and a pseudo measure (Nagelkerke R2) of explained variation was 43%. With the reduced model, however, 72% of cases were correctly classified, and a pseudo measure of explained variation was 30%. We note that this is a stringent test of the effects of conferencing on re-offending: one might have assumed that the control variables, especially pre-conferencing offending and our measure of social marginality, would have overwhelmed any potential conference effects. The control variables did account for most of the variability in predicting re-offending, and as we shall see, the odds ratios for these variables are large. However, the statistical significance of the two conference variables, coupled with the improvement in explained variation, suggests that they have unique effects. The odds ratios (in order of magnitude) for the full model show the following. The odds of re-offending are nearly nine times greater for youths who are residentially unstable (three or more residential changes on file with the police) compared to those with only one or two residential movements. Compared to other offenders, the odds of re-offending are three times greater for non-Aboriginal males. Youth with a history of prior offending have an odds of re-offending about three times greater than those with no detected prior offending. However, when particular conference features are present (offender remorse and consensual decision making), the odds of re-offending are reduced. When young people show remorse in the conference, the odds of re-offending are reduced by about a third (0.33); and when 22 outcome decisions are arrived at by genuine consensus, the odds of re-offending are reduced by about a quarter (0.27).20 While the odds ratios derived from the beta coefficients in Table 3 do not permit us to say how much more likely one outcome is over another, the relative risk ratio does (Agresti, 1990: 17-18). Translating the odds ratios from the 2 X 2 contingency tables for the predictors in the full model to risk ratios (i.e., cross-classifying the predictors with re- offending), we find that Aboriginal males and females were 2.57 times as likely to re-offend as non-Aboriginal offenders. Non-aboriginal males were equally likely to re-offend compared to other offenders (i.e., this dummy variable is independent of re-offending in the bivariate analysis; relative risk ratio = 0.982; odds ratio = 0.944). Those with prior offending were 1.79 times as likely to re-offend as those with no prior offending, and residentially unstable offenders (i.e., those with three or more residential addresses on their police record) were 3.79 times as likely to re-offend as more residentially stable youth. Conference-related variables seemed to diminish the likelihood of re-offending. Young offenders who were observed to be remorseful were 0.55 times as likely to re-offend as unremorseful youth. Also, offenders whose conference agreements were observed to be consensual were 0.74 times as likely to re-offend as offenders whose conference agreements were not. The odds ratios show that offender characteristics play a marked role in predicting future behavior; however, what happens in a conference may also be important. This outcome is consistent with Maxwell and Morris' (2001) findings from New Zealand, which 20 Several reviewers suggested that our single-item measures may not have adequately captured procedural justice and restorativeness and that a scale might be preferable. There are two key points we would make on this. First, we are not analyzing whether the presence of procedural justice or restorativeness generally predicts re-offending. In fact, the procedural justice variables were so consistently high, with little variability, they would be poor predictors, whether as single items or constructed as a scale. The variable "consensus in deciding the outcome" is reflective more of the agreement in negotiation amongst the parties (in particular, the offender and the police officer) than it is "fairness" or "respect"; perhaps for this reason, it has more variability and is more strongly predictive. Second, scales may be appropriate for some statistical analyses but not others. We decided, however, to create two additive scales for restorativeness and procedural justice by summing across the items listed in Table 2 and averaging them (i.e., scale scores ranged from 0 to 1). The mean restorativeness score and associated Cronbach's alpha were .46 (SD .24) and .75, and the mean procedural justice score and associated alpha were .83 (SD .13) and .26. The very low alpha for procedural justice likely flows from the low variance for many of the scale items (see Table 2). We entered these variables into a revised logistic regression model. The scale measures improved the model only slightly over the reduced model in Table 3, with 74% of cases correctly classified and a pseudo-R2 of 34%. The betas for restorativeness and procedural justice were -.82 (p=.49) and –3.02 (p=.17), respectively. The associated odds ratios were .44 and .05, respectively. Other variables entered into the revised model (sex/race-ethnicity, pre-conference offending, residential mobility) retained significance as in Equation 1 of Table 3. This is an instance when particular variables such as remorse are predictive of future behaviour (i.e, not re-offending) whereas a scale of "restorativeness", which includes many types of behaviours and interactions between offenders and victims, is not predictive. 23 show that prior offending and negative life experiences bear the heaviest on re-offending, but that re-offending is less likely when young people feel remorseful, are involved in conference decision-making, and agree with the conference outcome. We do not suggest that conferences "produce" remorseful youth who are less likely to re-offend, or that consensual decision- making has a causal impact on re-offending. It may be that some youth are already prepared to be remorseful at the conference and to be agreeable to outcome negotiations. It is not possible in this quantitative analysis to disentangle the effects of offender characteristics (that is, already feeling remorseful or readiness to negotiate an outcome) and a conference context that may encourage or promote these sensibilities, although this could be pursued in a qualitative analysis of selected cases.21 However, to the extent that certain behaviors and decision-making processes in conferences are indicative of future behavior, research from New Zealand and ours from South Australia show strikingly similar patterns. Consistency and reliability Colleagues and reviewers have queried the inter-rater reliability of the SAJJ observations, and thus we pause to consider questions of consistency and reliability. A decision was taken early in the project that only one SAJJ researcher should attend each conference. Even with the presence of one researcher, the coordinator and police officer were concerned with the influence this might have on the conference; two or more researchers would be excessive. Moreover, for ethical reasons, we wished to minimise the level of intrusion that research observations presented. One method of increasing consistency of observation is by developing a shared understanding of what the observational items mean; this was accomplished in the pre-research period as the Project Director (Daly) worked intensively with the SAJJ researchers in fashioning the items used in the observational protocol.22 However, there is another way to test the SAJJ results: by comparing them with 21 In a separate analysis of the SAJJ data, Daly (2003b) finds that the conference had an impact on young persons' views of the legal system. Those young people who stayed out of trouble were more likely to have positive views of the legal system, saying this was a result of the conference. 22 See Daly et al. (1998) for a discussion of instrument development. Daly first worked with the police officers in identifying and finalizing observational items, and revising the items further when working with the coordinators. Next, she wrote memos about the SAJJ observational instrument (which built in part on the police and coordinator surveys), which became the basis for intensive work with the SAJJ researchers in finalizing the SAJJ observational instrument. The aim was to develop items that made sense to the police and coordinators, and to create similar observational items across the three groups, although the SAJJ observational protocol was more detailed. 24 the observations of the police officers and coordinators in each conference. For the 89 conferences, five SAJJ observers and ten coordinators completed the conference observation protocol or survey; a higher number of police officers (N = 21) participated in conferences and completed the survey, with six officers involved in just one SAJJ conference. In light of these numbers (especially for the police), coupled with the different perspectives and experiences that members of each group may bring to the conference process, this is a demanding test of consistency and reliability. Our analysis finds a good to high degree of consistency across the key variables between the pairs (Appendix, Table A) and a high level of association between re-offending and the remorse and consensus variables (Appendix, Table B). In running the logistical regression analysis with the police officer and coordinator judgments of offender remorse and degree of genuine consensus, we find that while the SAJJ model is replicated by the coordinator model, it is partly replicated by the police model (Appendix, Table C). Specifically, remorse and conference consensus predicted re-offending in the coordinator model, but remorse (not conference consensus) predicted re-offending in the police model (see discussion in the Appendix). Conditional probabilities of re-offending Logistical regression odds ratios can be helpful in demonstrating the relative impact of individual offender and conference characteristics on re-offending. But in addition, logistic regression allows us to calculate the conditional probability of re-offending for various case scenarios (Poulos & Orchowsky, 1994; Hosmer & Lemeshow, 1989), by solving for the conditional probability = 1 / 1 + e –logit, where logit is the linear regression equation or logit transformation (B0 + B1X1 + … + BiXi). Using the coefficients from the SAJJ equation, we examined the impact of youth characteristics and conference elements on the probability of re-offending, and found that offender remorse and consensual decision-making lowered the probability of further offending. This was true for youth who possessed characteristics associated with further offending ("high-risk") and for those who did not ("low-risk") (see Table 4). When a young person was an Aboriginal male or female, residentially unstable, had a record of prior offending, and was not observed to be remorseful and the conference decision was not observed to be consensual (high-risk youth, poor conference elements), the conditional probably of a further offense was very high at .94. But when offender remorse and consensual decision-making were present for high-risk Aboriginal youth, the probability 25 of further offending decreased from .94 to .68.23 For a non-Aboriginal male with no prior offending history, who was residentially stable, who was observed to be remorseful and whose conference decision was observed to be consensual (low-risk youth, good conference elements), the conditional probability of re-offending was .11. But when good conference elements were absent for this youth (low-risk youth, poor conference elements), the probability of re-offending increased from .11 to .48. The shift in conditional probabilities of re-offending is more dramatic for high-risk non-Aboriginal females and low-risk Aboriginal males and females. For high-risk non-Aboriginal females, when good conference elements were absent, the conditional probability of offending was .80; but when good conference elements were present, it was .35. For low-risk Aboriginal males and females, when good conference elements were absent, the conditional probability of re-offending was .52; but when the elements were present, the probability was .12. WHO PREDICTS RE-OFFENDING BEST? Pooling the 1998 interview data from victims and offenders, the survey data from police officers and conference coordinators, and the observational data from SAJJ researchers, we cross-classified the responses to questions about the likelihood of future offending with our data on post-conference offending. In the interviews with young people in 1998, we asked them, "Do you think it likely or unlikely that you will be involved in a serious offense in the future?," and in the interviews with victims who attended the conference, we asked, "Do you think it likely or unlikely that the offender will be involved in a serious offense in the future?" The coordinator and police survey item, and the SAJJ observer item was, "Do you think it likely or unlikely that the young person will be involved in a serious offense in the future, one that comes to the attention of the police?" All were asked to answer on a four-point scale ranging from very likely to very unlikely, with an additional category of "do not know" or "unsure". The results show that the conference victims were least accurate in predicting young people's future offending (Table 5). Including the "do not know" and "unsure" responses, 46% of victims were correct in predicting future offending (or non-offending). The better predictors were the police (65%), offenders (60%), SAJJ observers (57%), and coordinators (55%). (If we remove the "do not know/unsure" category, the police and coordinators are the 23 We included the combined sex/race-ethnicity variable for Aboriginal males and females in the conditional probability calculations because it neared significance at the .10 level. 26 best predictors, making accurate predictions for about three-fourths of offenders.) False positives, that is, wrongly predicting future offending, were more frequent for the victims (38%) than for other groups; and not surprisingly, false negatives (predicting non-offending, when it did occur) were most frequent for the offenders (25%). Across the five groups, the coordinators were most likely to reserve judgment on re-offending with 26% saying they did not know or were unsure, whereas the percentages for the SAJJ observers, police, offenders, and victims were consistently smaller (10 to 13%) Several implications can be drawn from this analysis. The coordinators, police officers, and SAJJ observers not only have a more accurate view of a young person's future behavior (law-abiding and otherwise), but also they are more optimistic of the potential for young people to change, as evidenced by their relatively low percent of false positives. Members of these groups appear to believe in the potential for conferencing to promote change and social reintegration. By comparison, the conference victims appear to be more skeptical in the potential for conferencing, and they have a more static and negative view of offenders. One of the hallmarks of restorative justice (and re-integrative shaming) -- that the process should strive to separate the "badness" of acts from the identities of individuals committing them -- may be especially difficult for victims to contemplate and accept. Nevertheless, nearly 90% of conference victims recommended the government keep conferencing in the justice system. SUMMARY AND DISCUSSION New justice interventions such as conferencing are often required to demonstrate their claimed benefits by showing reductions in re-offending. Whether this should be a requirement is a matter of debate among researchers in the conferencing and restorative justice areas. Advocates and commentators give a variety of reasons for why conferencing is likely to be more effective than regular court processes in reducing crime. These include the positive (crime reduction) impact of how decisions are made and who participates in making them; changes in the sources of knowledge about crime and its impact (that is, away from lawyers to actual victims, offenders, and their supporters); changes in ways of thinking about sanctions and their purposes; and a renewed interest in justice system interactions as a form of moral education, a dialogic encounter intended to persuade and to show the offender how crime hurts victims and other members of the community. Analyzing how these and other elements may affect re-offending should be a focus of research and policy. However, to date, 27 this has not been the case. Rather, the more frequent approach is to compare measures of re- offending for different kinds of legal interventions. While such an approach has its place and should be carried out, it has limitations. Specifically, the problems of comparing court and conference in natural settings include sample selection bias by the police (or other referring group); differences in offenders' orientations to more immediately admit to an offense (or to deny it); and temporal differences in the handling of court and conference cases, which give different windows of time for measuring re-offending. These problems of comparison may be overcome with randomized field experiments, but these too have problems. Specifically, we noted that for an offender to be eligible for an experiment, a typical protocol is that s/he must admit to the offense first, before being assigned to court or conference. Offenders who admit early on to an offense may differ in theoretically important ways from those who do not. On ethical grounds, randomised field experiments are obliged to use this protocol. Nonetheless, it comes at a price of screening out a segment of arguably the most interesting people to study: those who may have more entrenched patterns of denial and who would be most likely to re-offend. Moreover, a significant problem for randomized field experiments is when to begin the clock in counting re-offending. The RISE project started the clock at the date of referral, and while there may be good reasons for this choice, it comes at the price of making accurate claims. If claims are to be made about the different effects of court and conference, a logical time to start the clock is after an offender has experienced the conference or court encounter, not before it. We have emphasized the benefits of studying re-offending by focusing on the variable qualities and effects within a conference (or restorative justice) practice. This approach permits an analysis of the theorized linkages between conference processes and re-offending, which can only be surmised or inferred when using a conference-court comparison. It is important that researchers take a more in-depth look at the conference process (or other similar process) in its own right to determine whether any of the claimed elements are present and with what impact. In taking this approach, we find that conferences have variable degrees of claimed elements present, and that this variability can be linked to re-offending. Specifically, holding constant previous offending and indicators of marginality, we find that young people, who were observed to be remorseful and who were in conferences where outcomes were achieved by genuine consensus, were less likely to re-offend. When extending the SAJJ model to the two other observers in the conference room (the police officer and coordinator), we find that offender remorse remains highly predictive, although 28 conference consensus is predictive for one group, but not the other. While we would have preferred a perfect replication of the SAJJ model, we are satisfied that these results add credibility to the SAJJ model. Research findings from a single jurisdiction can be limited in generalizability, but our results from South Australia are similar to those of Maxwell and Morris (2001) for New Zealand, and this gives them added weight. Our interpretations are also similar. Offenders come into the justice system with varied degrees of negative life experiences, social marginality and disadvantage, and previous contact with the justice system. We would expect these factors to have a strong impact on predicting future offending, irrespective of the character of any justice system intervention. Over and above these factors, both the SAJJ project and Maxwell and Morris (2001) find that conference-specific factors are indicative of reduced re-offending, in particular, offender remorse and involvement in decision-making. Based on these statistical results, we cannot make a causal claim that conferences induce remorse or contrition or that consensually-based outcomes cause reductions in re-offending. To make such a claim would require an analysis of offenders' pre-conference orientations and the significance of the conference in the life of the young person and his or her supporters. Moreover, offenders, victims, and their supporters come to conferences with varying degrees of knowledge about the process and what they are expected to do; these factors likely affect the probability of good conference elements emerging (or not). Jurisdictions in Australia and New Zealand vary in pre-conference preparation by coordinators. Some jurisdictions (like Queensland) routinely have face-to-face pre-conference meetings with victims and offenders, whereas other jurisdictions (South Australia and the ACT) do not. We have tried to make a case for the benefits of studying within-conference variation for predicting re-offending, but we recognize its limitations. Specifically, policymakers may be more impressed with comparisons of different legal interventions, especially if a new one can be shown to outperform an older, more established form. In comparing the benefits of conference over court, however, researchers need to specify which behaviors and interactions occur in conferences more often than in court, which are then linked to reductions in re- offending. From the recidivism literature and our analysis, such reductions will be at the margins, with other variables such as pre-conference offending and social marginality having substantially greater influences. Our analysis shows that while about one-quarter of young people were changed by the conference process toward more law-abiding behavior, the victims attending conferences 29 were skeptical of the capacity for youthful offenders to change. Despite the fact that two- thirds of conference victims believed the young person who victimized them or their property would be in trouble again, close to 90% of them said the government should keep family conferencing. Victims therefore distinguish between seeing conferencing as a good thing, to be maintained, and holding ambivalent (and inaccurate) attitudes about the potential for youthful lawbreakers to change. These results lead us to speculate that in supporting a new justice idea in the youth justice area, evidence of reductions in re-offending may be more salient to policymakers or politicians than to their constituents. 30 REFERENCES Agresti, A. (1990). Categorical Data Analysis. New York: Wiley. Ahmed, E., Harris, N., Braithwaite, J., & Braithwaite, V. (2001). Shame Management through Reintegration. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Bargen, J. (1996). Kids, cops, courts, conferencing and children's rights: a note on perspectives. Australian Journal of Human Rights, 2, 209-228. Braithwaite, J. (1989). Crime, Shame and Reintegration. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Braithwaite, J. (1999). Restorative justice: assessing optimistic and pessimistic accounts. Crime and Justice: A Review of Research, 25, 1-127. Braithwaite, J. & Mugford, S. (1994). Conditions of successful reintegration ceremonies. British Journal of Criminology, 34, 139-171. Bushway, S., Piquero, A., Briody, L., Cauffman, E. & Mazerolle, P. (2001). An empirical framework for studying desistance as a process. Criminology, 39, 491-516 Consedine, J. & Bowen, H., eds. (1999). Restorative Justice: Contemporary Themes and Practice. Lyttelton, New Zealand: Ploughshares Publications. Daly, K. (2001a). Conferencing in Australia and New Zealand: variations, research findings, and prospects. In A. Morris and G. Maxwell (eds.), Restorative Justice for Juveniles: Conferencing, Mediation and Circles. Oxford: Hart Publishing. Daly, K. (2001b). South Australia Juvenile Justice (SAJJ) Technical Report No. 2: Research Instruments in Year 2 (1999) and Background Notes. Brisbane: School of Criminology and Criminal Justice, Griffith University. Available at http://www.aic.gov.au/rjustice/sajj/index.html Daly, K. (2002). Restorative justice: the real story. Punishment & Society, 4, 55-79. Daly, K. (2003a). Mind the gap: restorative justice in theory and practice. In A. von Hirsch, J. Roberts, A. E. Bottoms, K. Roach, & M. Schiff (eds.) Restorative Justice and Criminal Justice: Competing or Reconcilable Paradigms?. Oxford: Hart Publishing. Daly, K. (2003b). Making variation a virtue: evaluating the potential and limits of restorative justice. In E. Weitekamp & H. Kerner (eds.) Restorative Justice in Context: International Practice and Directions. Devon, England: Willan Publishing. Daly, K. & Hayes, H. (2001). Restorative justice and conferencing in Australia. Trends and Issues in Criminal Justice No. 186. Canberra: Australian Institute of Criminology. Available at http://www.aic.gov.au/publications/tandi/tandi186.html 31 Daly, K. & Immarigeon, R. (1998). The past, present, and future of restorative justice: some critical reflections. Contemporary Justice Review, 1, 31-45. Daly, K, Venables, M., McKenna, M., Mumford, L. & Christie-Johnston, J (1998). South Australia Juvenile Justice (SAJJ) Research on Conferencing, Technical Report No. 1: Project Overview and Research Instruments. Brisbane: School of Criminology and Criminal Justice, Griffith University. Available at http://www.aic.gov.au/rjustice/sajj/index.html Dignan, J. (1991). Repairing the Damage: An Evaluation of an Experimental Adult Reparation Scheme in Kettering, Northamptonshire. Sheffield, England: Centre for Criminological and Legal Research, University of Sheffield. Dignan, J. (1992). Repairing the damage: can reparation be made to work in the service of diversion? British Journal of Criminology, 32, 453-472. Garfinkel, H. (1956). Conditions of successful degradation ceremonies. American Journal of Sociology, 61, 420-424. Gendreau, P, Little, T. & Goggin, C. (1996). A meta-analysis of the predictors of adult offender recidivism: what works! Criminology, 34, 575-607. Hayes, H, Prenzler, T & Wortley, R. (1998). Making Amends: Final Evaluation of the Queensland Community Conferencing Pilot. Griffith University: Centre for Crime Policy and Public Policy. Available at http://www.gu.edu.au/school/ccj/amends.pdf . Harris, N. & Burton, J. (1996). The Reliability of Observed Reintegrative Shaming, Shame, Defiance and Other Key Concepts in Diversionary Conferences: RISE Working Paper Number 5. Canberra: Australian National University. Available at http://www.aic.gov.au/rjustice/rise/working/risepap5/risepap5.pdf Harris, N. & Burton, J. (1998). Testing the reliability of observational measures of reintegrative shaming at community accountability conferences and at court. Australian and New Zealand Journal of Criminology, 31, 230-241. Hesmer, D. & Lemeshow, S. (1989). Applied Logistic Regression. New York: John Wiley & Sons. Kurki, L. (2001). Evaluation of restorative justice practices. Paper presented to Cambridge Seminar on Restorative Justice, Toronto, May. Latimer, J., Dowden, C. & Muise, D. (2001). The Effectiveness of Restorative Justice Practices: A Meta-Analysis. Department of Justice: Research and Statistics Division. Available at http://canada.justice.gc.ca/en/ps/rs/rep/meta-b-e.html 32 Laub, J. & Sampson, R. (2001). Understanding desistance from crime. Crime and Justice: An Annual Review of Research. Chicago, Ill.: University of Chicago Press. Luke, G. & Lind, B. (2002). Reducing juvenile crime: conferencing versus court. Crime and Justice Bulletin: Contemporary Issue in Crime and Justice. New South Wales Bureau of Crime Statistics and Research. Available at http://www.lawlink.nsw.gov.au/bocsar1.nsf/files/CJB69.pdf/$file/CJB69.pdf Maltz, M. (1984). Recidivism. New York: Academic Press. Matza, D. (1964). Delinquency and Drift. New York: Wiley. Marshall, T. (1999). Restorative Justice: An Overview. London: Home Office. Marshall, T. (1992). Restorative justice on trial in Britain. In H. Messmer and H.-U. Otto (eds.) Restorative Justice on Trial. Rotterdam: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Maxwell, G. & Morris, A. (1993). Family, Victims and Culture: Youth Justice in New Zealand. Wellington: Institute of Criminology, Victoria University of New Zealand. Maxwell, G. & Morris, A. (2001). Family group conferences and reoffending. In A. Morris and G. Maxwell (eds.), Restorative Justice for Juveniles: Conferencing, Mediation and Circles. Oxford: Hart Publishing. McCold, P. & Wachtel, B. (1998). Restorative Policing Experiment: The Bethlehem, Pennsylvania Police Family Conferencing Project. Pipersville, PA: Community Service Foundation. McGarrell, E. (2001). Restorative Justice Conferences as an Early Response to Young Offenders. Washington DC: Office of Juvenile Justice and Delinquency Prevention, US Department of Justice. Messmer, H. & Otto, H. (1992). Restorative justice: steps on the way to a good idea. In H. Messmer & H.-U. Otto (eds.), Restorative Justice on Trial. Rotterdam: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Miers, D. (2001). An International Review of Restorative Justice. Crime Reduction Research Series Paper 10. London: Home Office. Available at http://www.homeoffice.gov.uk/rds/prgpdfs/crrs10.pdf Miers, D., Maguire, M., Goldie, S., Sharpe, K., Hale, C., Netten, A., Uglow, S., Doolin, K., Hallam, A., Enterkin, J. & Newburn, T. (2001). An Exploratory Evaluation of Restorative Justice Schemes. Crime Reduction Research Series Paper 9. London: Home Office. Available at http://www.homeoffice.gov.uk/rds/prgpdfs/crrs09.pdf 33 Morris, A. & Gelsthorpe, L. (2000). Something old, something borrowed, something blue, but something new? A comment on the prospects for restorative justice under the Crime and Disorder Act 1998. Criminal Law Review, Jan, 18-30. Morris, A. & Maxwell, G. (1997). Family group conferences and convictions. Occasional Papers in Criminology New Series No. 5. Wellington, New Zealand: Institute of Criminology, Victoria University of Wellington. Poulos, T. & Orchowsky, S. (1994). Serious juvenile offenders: predicting the probability of transfer to criminal court. Crime and Delinquency, 40, 3-17. Schneider, A. (1986). Restitution and recidivism rates of juvenile offenders: results from four experimental studies. Criminology, 24, 533-552. Sherman, L. (1993). Defiance, deterrence, and irrelevance: a theory of the criminal sanction. Journal of Research in Crime and Delinquency, 30, 445-473. Sherman, L., Strang, H. & Woods, D. (2000). Recidivism Patterns in the Canberra Reintegrative Shaming Experiments (RISE). Canberra: Centre for Restorative Justice, Research School of Social Sciences, Australian National University. Strang, H, Barnes, G., Braithwaite, J. & Sherman, L. (1999). Experiments in Restorative Policing: A Progress Report on the Canberra Reintegrative Shaming Experiments. Canberra: Australian Federal Police and Australian National University. Available at http://www.aic.gov.au/rjustice/rise/index.html Tyler, T. (1990). Why People Obey the Law. New Haven: Yale University Press. Umbreit, M. & Coates, R. (1993). Cross-site analysis of victim offender mediation in four states. Crime and Delinquency, 39, 565-585. Umbreit, M, Coates, R. & Vos, B. (2001). Victim impact of meeting with young offenders: two decades of victim offender mediation practice and research. In A. Morris and G. Maxwell (eds.), Restorative Justice for Juveniles: Conferencing, Mediation and Circles. Oxford: Hart Publishing. van Ness, D. & Schiff, M. (2001). Satisfaction guaranteed? The meaning of satisfaction in restorative justice. In G. Bazemore and M. Schiff (eds.), Restorative Community Justice. Cincinnati, OH: Anderson Publishing Company. Walgrave, L. (1999). Community service as a cornerstone of a systemic restorative response to (juvenile) crime. In G. Bazemore and L. Walgrave (eds.), Restorative Juvenile Justice: Repairing the Harm of Youth Crime. Monsey, NY: Criminal Justice Press. 34 Young, R. (2001). Just cops doing "shameful" business? Police-led restorative justice and the lessons of research. In A. Morris and G. Maxwell (eds.), Restorative Justice for Juveniles: Conferencing, Mediation and Circles. Oxford: Hart Publishing. 35 Table 1. Pre- and post-conference offending Official contact includes any incident that led to a formal caution, conference, or court disposition. (N=89) pre-conference contact: 0 (except SAJJ case) 43% 1 27 2+ 30 3+ 17 4+ 14 5+ 7 post-conference contact: 0 60% 1 17 2+ 23 3+ 18 4+ 11 5+ 10 Group Offended pre-SAJJ conference Offended post-SAJJ conference Percentage of primary offenders (N=89) Experimenters no no 34 Desisters yes no 26 Drifters no yes 9 Persisters yes yes 32 1 Table 2. Bivariate relationships between selected variables and re-offending Variable Categories Percent re- offending Phi Offender-related variables Sex (76% male) 1=male 0-female 43 33 .08 Racial-ethnic identity (12% Aboriginal) 1=Aboriginal 0=non-Aboriginal 64 37 .18* Number of addresses on police file (28% 3 or more) 1=3+ 0=1 to 2 72 28 .40** Pre-SAJJ conference offending (57% yes) 1=yes 0=no 55 21 .34** Offense-related variables Type of offense (44% violent) 1=violent 0=property 36% 44% -.08 Victim-offender relationship (52% known) 1=known 0=stranger 32% 50% -.18* Type of victim (80% personal) 1=personal 0=organization only 37% 56% -.16 Conference-related variables Victim or representative present (80% yes) Victim only present (74% yes) 1=yes 0=no 1=yes 0=no 41% 39% 41% 39% .02 .02 Conference was a waste of time (10% yes) 1=yes 0=no 78% 36% .26** Angry/aggressive remarks aimed at offender (10% yes) 1=yes 0=no 57% 39% .10 Crying by participants (25% yes) 1=yes 0=no 46% 39% .06 Measures of restorativeness Offender gave a clear story (71% mostly or fully) 1=mostly or fully 0=somewhat or not at all 43% 35% .08 Offender accepted responsibility (62% mostly or fully) 1=mostly or fully 0=somewhat or not at all 35% 50% -.15 Offender actively involved (78% mostly or fully) 1=mostly or fully 0=somewhat or not at all 36% 55% -.16 Offender was defiant (30% somewhat, mostly or fully) 1=somewhat, mostly or fully 0=not at all 52% 36% .15 YP was remorseful (49% mostly or fully) 1=mostly or fully 0=somewhat or not at all 27% 53% -.27** Offender offered spontaneous apology (41% mostly or fully)‡ 1=mostly or fully 0=somewhat or not at all 33% 46% -.13 Offender assured victim offense wouldn't happen again (58% mostly or fully) ‡ 1=mostly or fully 0=somewhat or not at all 34% 50% -.16 Offender understood impact of crime on victim (52% mostly or fully) ‡ 1=mostly or fully 0=somewhat or not at all 41% 41% .00 2 Table 2 cont. Victim effectively described impact of offense (72% mostly or fully) ‡ 1=mostly or fully 0=somewhat or not at all 39% 45% -.05 Victim understood offender's situation (34% mostly or fully) ‡ 1=mostly or fully 0=somewhat or not at all 46% 38% .07 Conference ended on a high (55% yes)† 1=yes 0=no 33% 50% -.18* Positive movement or mutual understanding between offender and victim expressed in words (31% mostly or fully) ‡ 1=mostly or fully 0=somewhat or not at all 41% 41% .00 Positive movement or mutual understanding between offender and victim expressed symbolically (20% mostly or fully) ‡ 1=mostly or fully 0=somewhat or not at all 36% 42% -.05 Measures of procedural justice Process of deciding outcome was fair (89% yes) 1=yes 0=no 39% 50% -.07 Conference coordinator negotiated outcome well (89% yes) 1=yes 0=no 41% 40% .00 Outcome decided by genuine consensus (64% yes) 1=yes 0=no (offender accepts/accepts with reluctance police officer's modification of outcome) 33% 53% -.19* Offender understood relationship between offense and outcome (80% mostly or fully) 1=mostly or fully 0=somewhat or not at all 37% 56% -.16 Offender appeared "powerless" in room full of adults (38% some/fair/to high degree) 1=some/fair/to high degree 0=not at all 47% 36% .11 Police officer treated the offender with respect (99% agree) 1=agree 0=disagree 41% 0% .09 Offender treated police officer with respect (96% agree) 1=agree 0=disagree 38% 100% -.26** Coordinator permitted everyone to have a say (98% agree) 1=agree 0=disagree 39% 100% -.18 Coordinator seemed impartial (93% agree) 1=agree 0=disagree 41% 33% .04 † "Ended on a high" refers to the SAJJ observer's determination that there was mutual good will and positive movement between the offender and victim by the end of the conference. ‡ Percentages are based on the 71 conferences for which a victim (or victim representative) was present. * p < .10 ** p < .05 3 Table 3. Logistic regression results for offender and conference characteristics and re- offending (1 = re-offending) Equation 1: Full model Predictor Beta Odds ratio Sex/race-ethnicity (1=Aboriginal male or female) 1.66 5.31 Sex/race-ethnicity (1=non-Aboriginal male) 1.52** 4.55 Pre-conference offending (1=yes) 1.09* 2.97 3 or more residential movements (1=yes) 2.17** 8.75 Offender showed remorse (1=yes) -1.12** .33 Genuine consensus in outcome decision (1=yes) -1.30** .27 Constant (B0) -1.59* N = 89 80% cases correctly classified Pseudo-R2 = 43% χ2 = 34.0 *** Equation 2: Reduced model Predictor Beta Odds ratio Sex/race-ethnicity (1=Aboriginal male or female) 1.49 4.45 Sex/race-ethnicity (1=non-Aboriginal male) 1.29* 3.63 Pre-conference offending (1=yes) 1.11** 3.04 3 or more residential movements (1=yes) 1.73** 5.67 Constant (B0) -2.65** N = 89 72% cases correctly classified Pseudo-R2 = 30% χ2 = 23.0 *** * p < .10 ** p < .05 4 Table 4. Conditional probabilities of re-offending for various case scenarios Predictor Logit B0 + B1 … + Bi Probability 1 / 1 + e -logit Aboriginal young people, male and female Scenario 1 – high-risk youth, poor conference elements 3.338 .94 Sex/race-ethnicity (1=Aboriginal male or female) Pre-conference offending (1=yes) Three or more residential movements (1=yes) Offender showed remorse (0=no) Genuine consensus in outcome decision (0=no) Scenario 2 – high-risk youth, good conference elements .922 .68 Sex/race-ethnicity (1=Aboriginal male or female) Pre-conference offending (1=yes) Three or more residential movements (1=yes) Offender showed remorse (1=yes) Genuine consensus in outcome decision (1=yes) Scenario 3 – low-risk youth, poor conference elements .079 .52 Sex/race-ethnicity (1=Aboriginal male or female) Pre-conference offending (0=yes) Three or more residential movements (0=yes) Offender showed remorse (0=no) Genuine consensus in outcome decision (0=no) Scenario 4 – low-risk youth, good conference elements -2.337 .12 Sex/race-ethnicity (1=Aboriginal male or female) Pre-conference offending (0=yes) Three or more residential movements (0=yes) Offender showed remorse (1=yes) Genuine consensus in outcome decision (1=yes) non-Aboriginal young people Scenario 5 – high-risk male, poor conference elements 3.184 .93 Sex/race-ethnicity (1=non-Aboriginal male) Pre-conference offending (1=yes) Three or more residential movements (1=yes) Offender showed remorse (0=no) Genuine consensus in outcome decision (0=no) Scenario 6 – high-risk female, poor conference elements 1.669 .80 Sex/race-ethnicity (0=non-Aboriginal female) Pre-conference offending (1=yes) Three or more residential movements (1=yes) Offender showed remorse (0=no) Genuine consensus in outcome decision (0=no) Scenario 7 – high-risk male, good conference elements .768 .65 Sex/race-ethnicity (1=non-Aboriginal male) Pre-conference offending (1=yes) Three or more residential movements (1=yes) Offender showed remorse (1=yes) Genuine consensus in outcome decision (1=yes) 5 Table 4 cont. Scenario 8 – high-risk female, good conference elements -.747 .35 Sex/race-ethnicity (0=non-Aboriginal female) Pre-conference offending (1=yes) Three or more residential movements (1=yes) Offender showed remorse (1=yes) Genuine consensus in outcome decision (1=yes) Scenario 9 – low-risk male, poor conference elements -.075 .48 Sex/race-ethnicity (1=non-Aboriginal male) Pre-conference offending (0=no) Three or more residential movements (0=no) Offender showed remorse (0=no) Genuine consensus in outcome decision (0=no) Scenario 10 – low-risk female, poor conference elements -1.59 .21 Sex/race-ethnicity (0=non-Aboriginal female) Pre-conference offending (0=no) Three or more residential movements (0=no) Offender showed remorse (0=no) Genuine consensus in outcome decision (0=no) Scenario 11 – low-risk male, good conference elements -2.491 .11 Sex/race-ethnicity (1=non-Aboriginal male) Pre-conference offending (0=no) Three or more residential movements (0=no) Offender showed remorse (1=yes) Genuine consensus in outcome decision (1=yes) Scenario 12 – low-risk female, good conference elements -4.006 .03 Sex/race-ethnicity (0=non-Aboriginal female) Pre-conference offending (0=no) Three or more residential movements (0=no) Offender showed remorse (1=yes) Genuine consensus in outcome decision (1=yes) 6 Table 5. Predictions of re-offending by SAJJ observers, police officers, coordinators, offenders, and victims SAJJ observers (N=89) Police officers (N=89) Coordi- nators (N=89) Offenders (N=93) Conference victims (N=61) Correctly predicted offending or non-offending 57% 65% 55% 60% 46% False positive (wrongly predicted offending) 17% 14% 10% 3% 38% False negative (wrongly predicted non-offending) 16% 11% 9% 25% 3% Do not know or unsure 10% 10% 26% 12% 13% Summary Correct prediction, all cases 57% 65% 55% 60% 46% Correct prediction, excluding do not know or unsure 64% 73% 74% 68% 53% Note: Predictions made by SAJJ observers, police officers, and coordinators were of the 89 primary offenders in conferences having multiple offenders. Predictions were made by all of the offenders interviewed in 1998 and the conference victims interviewed in 1998. 7 APPENDIX There was a generally good degree of consistency across the police, coordinators, and SAJJ observers for remorse (paired group comparisons ranged from 57% to 66% agreement, see Appendix, Table A) and an even higher level of consistency for judgements about how conferences ended, that is, "on a high" (paired group comparisons ranged from 73% to 75% agreement). The same is true for judgements about whether a conference was a "waste of time". Paired group comparisons for SAJJ observers, police officers, and coordinators showed that agreement rates ranged from 69% (between coordinator and police officer) to 90% (between SAJJ observer and coordinator). For characterising the outcome decision (which had three options, "genuine consensus", "acceptance", and "acceptance with reluctance"), the paired group comparisons ranged from 60% (between coordinator and police officer) to 71% (between the SAJJ observer and coordinator). In general we find that the police officers tended to view the conference and the offender's behaviour more optimistically and positively than the coordinators and researchers. When, in 1999, the results of the coordinator and police surveys were presented to these groups, they were initially surprised to see the higher ratings by the police for many items. If anything, the two groups would have expected the reverse. The explanation the police gave was that compared to what they saw in the field or in the station, the civility of the offender and other conference participants, coupled with the coolness of the deliberative process, was a decided improvement. In light of the high numbers in each group (5 researchers, 10 coordinators, and 21 police officers), the fact that the coordinators and police officers are criminal justice workers, not researchers, and several items asked them to judge their own behaviour, we are pleased with the levels of agreement across the three groups. For comparison, we summarize the inter-rater reliability of similar items in the RISE project. Harris and Burton (1996, 1998) assessed the agreement rates for observers (2 per conference or court case) in a sample of 45 RISE conference and court cases. Following each case, observers independently completed a "global observation instrument" consisting of 40 questions asking observers to rate various aspects of the case – e.g., "How much reintegrative shaming was expressed?", "How sorry/remorseful was the offender for their actions?" Item responses were given on an 8- point Likert scale ("none" to "very much"; "not at all sorry" to "very sorry"). Agreement rates across the 40 items ranged from 42% to 98% agreement. For "How much reintegrative shaming was expressed?", overall agreement (i.e., for conference and court cases) was 80%. 8 For "How sorry/remorseful was the offender for their actions", overall agreement was 73%. Agreement was much lower for items relating to the outcome decision. For "How much did the offender contribute to the conference/court outcome?", overall agreement was 53%. Similarly, for "How much was the offender coerced into accepting the conference/court case outcome?", overall agreement was 49%. Because our agreement rates are similar to those achieved in the RISE research for judgements about remorse and higher for judgements about outcome decisions, even across groups of observers from very different professional backgrounds, our view is that the SAJJ observations are reliable. An analysis of the phi coefficients of re-offending with the police and coordinator remorse and consensus variables showed that both were significantly related to re-offending for both groups (Appendix, Table B). We also ran the logistic regression analysis, using the police and coordinator remorse and genuine consensus variables (see Appendix, Table C). When police measures of remorse and consensus were entered, the model correctly classified 79% of cases and explained 52% of the variation in re-offending. When the coordinator measures were entered, the model correctly classified 78% of cases and explained 42% of the variation in post-intervention offending. In both the police model and coordinator model, remorse remained a significant predictor. The consensus variable neared statistical significance for the coordinators; thus, we are satisfied that the coordinator model replicates the SAJJ model. However, consensus was not a significant predictor of re-offending for the police in the logistic regression analysis. We suspect that one reason for this result is that the remorse variable was so highly predictive of re-offending for the police, it overwhelmed the effect of the consensus variable. 9 Appendix Table A. Paired group comparisons on key conference variables (remorse, consensus, waste of time, ended on high), percent with same judgments "To what extent was the YP remorseful for their actions?" (mostly/fully) coordinator police officer SAJJ observer coordinator - 66 57 police officer - - 64 SAJJ observer - - - "How would you characterise the outcome decision?" (genuine consensus) coordinator police officer SAJJ observer coordinator - 60 71 police officer - - 69 SAJJ observer - - - "The conference was largely a waste of time." (agree/strongly agree) coordinator police officer SAJJ observer coordinator - 69 90 police officer - - 70 SAJJ observer - - - "The conference ended on a 'high' – a positive note of repair and goodwill." (agree/strongly agree) coordinator police officer SAJJ observer coordinator - 75 73 police officer - - 75 SAJJ obsever - - - Appendix Table B. Bivariate relationships between selected variables and re-offending for coordinator and police Remorse Coordinator: YP was remorseful (54% mostly or fully) 1=mostly or fully 0=somewhat or not at all 27% 59% -.34** Police: YP was remorseful (56% mostly or fully) 1=mostly or fully 0=somewhat or not at all 20% 66% -.47** Genuine consensus Coordinator: Outcome decided by genuine consensus (51% yes) 1=yes 0=no (offender accepts/accepts with reluctance police officer's modification of outcome) 31% 50% -.19* Police: Outcome decided by genuine consensus (48% yes) 1=yes 0=no (offender accepts/accepts with reluctance police officer's modification of outcome) 30% 50% -.20* * p < .10 ** p < .05 10 Appendix Table C. Logistic regression results for offender and conference characteristics and re-offending (1 = re-offending) "Coordinator model" Predictor Beta Odds ratio Sex/race-ethnicity (1=Aboriginal male or female) 1.27 3.57 Sex/race-ethnicity (1=non-Aboriginal male) 1.22* 3.42 Pre-conference offending (1=yes) 1.40** 4.06 3 or more residential movements (1=yes) 1.73** 5.64 Offender showed remorse (1=yes) -1.35** .26 Genuine consensus in outcome decision (1=yes) -0.81 .45 Constant (B0) -1.67** N = 89 78% cases correctly classified Pseudo-R2 = 42% χ2 = 33.6 ** "Police model" Predictor Beta Odds ratio Sex/race-ethnicity (1=Aboriginal male or female) 1.49 4.44 Sex/race-ethnicity (1=non-Aboriginal male) 1.85** 6.36 Pre-conference offending (1=yes) 1.51** 4.54 3 or more residential movements (1=yes) 1.71** 5.54 Offender showed remorse (1=yes) -2.35** .10 Genuine consensus in outcome decision (1=yes) -0.48 .62 Constant (B0) -1.84** N = 89 79% cases correctly classified Pseudo-R2 = 52% χ2 = 43.7 ** * p < .10 ** p < .05 YOUTH JUSTICE CONFERENCING AND RE-OFFENDING* RESEARCH ON RESTORATIVE JUSTICE, CONFERENCING, AND RE-OFFENDING Table 1. Pre- and post-conference offending Summary "How would you characterise the outcome decision?" (genuine consensus) "The conference was largely a waste of time." (agree/strongly agree) "The conference ended on a 'high' – a positive note of repair and goodwill." (agree/strongly agree) work_huzvkblxpbe4fjfzevn5v3fvga ---- Book reviews 59 ethics. This range means that the collection can be read in two main ways. First, it can be read simply for factual information. In this respect, perhaps unsurprisingly, it is the con- tributions that are predominantly medicine-based and law-based that are generally the most useful. Secondly, the book can be read for clarification of the ethical issues surrounding reproductive technology. Here, the reader is immediately confronted by a catholicity of the concepts of ethics. For example, ethics refers sometimes to what appears on the agenda of a hospital ethics commit- tee (in Richard West's contribution), to a specific moral or religious stance which is commended to practitioners (in the contributions of Richard Lilford and Jack Mahoney), and sometimes to a branch of academic philosophy (in Anne Fagot-Largeault's contribution). This catholicity does of course represent the wide range of opinion in medical ethics, but in a single collec- tion it inevitably poses a problem. Despite the convenient grouping of the book according to substantive topics, the sheer range of approaches makes it difficult for the reader to identify the precise points at which different contributors would agree or disagree. The discussions go part of the way towards such an identifica- tion, but, like most conference dis- cussions, they reveal a fair amount of mutual misunderstanding between contributors. It is probably for these reasons that the most successful part of the book is where withholding neonatal care is examined first by Alexander Campbell as a paediatri- cian and, in response, by Jennifer Jackson as a philosopher. Here, and in the usefully delimited discussion that follows, genuine debate is discernible, taking the level of analysis beyond that of mere juxtaposition of diverse views. ELIZABETH KINGDOM Department of Sociology, Social Policy and Social Work Studies, University of Liverpool. Protecting the vulnerable: autonomy and consent in health care Edited by Margaret Brazier and Mary Lobjoit, 183 pages + xi, London, 1991. Routledge, £30.00 This volume in the 'Social ethics and policy' series is a collection of papers, some of which were originally given as part of a public lecture series in Manchester in 1988. The unifying theme is the ethical and legal problems of making health-care decisions in cases where patients are, or at least are thought to be, partially or completely incapable of making valid decisions for themselves. This unity at one level of course conceals enormous variety at another, since the forms which such actual or apparent incompetence can take are incredibly varied, as are the decisions which have to be taken in providing care for such patients. The ethical problems generated are equally varied. Thus the papers range over very premature babies, people with mental handicap, women undergoing sterilisation, subjects of non-therapeutic research, people with suicidal tendencies and those receiving psychotherapy, especially students. In addition to the discussions of particular types of decision, there are also more theoreti- cal papers about the nature of auto- nomy, informed consent and the right to information. The papers on particular types of case are on the whole sensible, practical and sensitive, but hardly ground- breaking. The policy recommenda- tions made are usually plainly right but there often seems to be a reluc- tance really to get to grips with the ethical complexities of a situation. For instance, Heather Draper, writing about the sterilisation of mentally handicapped women, recommends a review of the law concerning wardship and research into the attitudes of mentally disabled women towards pregnancy, labour and children - both eminently sensible suggestions. But the ethical issue in such cases - the balance to be drawn between the interests of the woman herself, those of the people who care for her and those of the potential child - is referred to but never really explored in her paper, and she comes to the conclusion that sterilisations must be 'solely in the interests of the individual concerned'. An exception to this line of criticism is Gavin Fairbairn's paper 'Suicide and justified paternalism'. Drawing both on his reflections on his own profes- sional experience and on a subtle philosophical analysis, Fairbairn succeeds in moving beyond the tired discussions of the right to suicide and gives an account of the ethics of pre- venting suicide which makes due allowance for the interests of those other than the suicider who are involved. In the course of this, he also has interesting general things to say about, for instance, paternalism: much, he says, of what passes for paternalism is really 'self-interested pseudo-paternalism because it is more concerned with protecting its perpe- trator than with caring for the welfare of the individual in question'. The more theoretical papers are variable in quality. Margaret Brazier very thoroughly examines the legal problems of treating incompetent patients, but rightly concludes that the rights of, for example, mentally handicapped people depend far more on general social attitudes to disabled people than on legal frameworks. Richard Lindley's paper on a doctor's duty to inform patients of the facts in cases of surgery comes to interesting conclusions, recommending a form of the Bolam test which takes in groups other than medical experts. Harry Lesser provides a useful discussion of the patient's right to information. Alastair Campbell's paper, however, seems simply confused. He makes great play with the notion that patients are dependent on their doctors, as they clearly are, but seems to think that that implies limits to the value of patient autonomy rather than being precisely the reason why respect for patient autonomy is needed. ERIC MATTHEWS Department of Philosophy, University ofAberdeen. Organ replacement therapy: ethics, justice, commerce First joint meeting of ESOT (European Society for Organ Transplantation) and EDTA/ERA(European Renal Association) in Munich, 11-14 December, 1990. Edited by W Land and J B Dossetor, 578 pages + xxiii, London and Berlin, 1991. Springer- Verlag, ,C78.50 The contents pages of this volume list 81 papers, five transcripts of plenary discussion sessions, and 201 contri- butors, giving some idea as to the huge input the conference it is based upon received. The articles range in kind from those which are more or less purely medical, though having o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://jm e .b m j.co m / J M e d E th ics: first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /jm e .1 9 .1 .5 9 -a o n 1 M a rch 1 9 9 3 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://jme.bmj.com/ 60 Book reviews some bearing on certain kind of moral discussion, for instance, 'Results of an Audit of Living Related Renal Allograft Donation from a Single Centre', all the way to those which are more or less entirely moral philoso- phy, though having some bearing on what one should or should not do in transplant surgery, for example, 'Is There a Universal System of Ethics, or Are Ethics Culture Specific?' There is an attempt here to cover all of the current ethical debates in transplantation medicine; the book includes papers related to living donor organ donation, to the buying and selling of organs and the growing international business in transplanta- tion, to the problems associated with cadaver explantation, and to the dif- ficulties of fair distribution of the restricted numbers of organs avail- able for transplant. At the same time, the volume gives an idea of the state of the art in transplant techniques, and some sense of where the cutting edge of this branch of medical sci- ence might be. Partial liver trans- plants, domino heart transplants, pig-person transplants, fetal tissue transplants, all have articles devoted to them in these pages. An omission, however, is any direct consideration of the current position on artificial organs. Organ Replacement Therapy, looked at as a philosophical discussion of moral issues, will inevitably leave something to be desired. The argu- ments of the lawyers, theologians, philosophers and doctors, are unavoidably underdeveloped. The first, and more significant, con- sequence of this is that fundamental assertions made by contributors sometimes escape scrutiny. For instance, in the discussion of brain death (is it tantamount to death?) all participants base their arguments on the distinction between 'person' and 'human being' and the impression given is that this is a settled fact of life. It is nothing of the sort. A second, less serious, consequence is that where other assumptions (for instance that clinicians should be involved in organ allocation decisions) are put under the microscope, and subjected to useful inspection, the discussion is shortlived and inconclusive. It is perhaps most accurate to describe this book as a panoramic snapshot (if that is not a contradic- tion in terms) of the huge and com- plex scenery of transplant medicine and ethics at a particular moment in its evolution. Most interestingly, that panorama shows distinct and, on occasion, contradictory, cultural perspectives. One instance of this is the discussion of the morality of rewarded gifting (that is, offering an organ donor something, over and above compensation, for the dona- tion of his or her organ). Into this discussion are fed views from India, Iran, and Pakistan, as well as the perhaps more familiar perspectives of Western Europe and North America. The value of Organ Replacement Therapy, then, lies not in its taking a moral idea and subjecting it to rigorous and careful philosophical scrutiny, but rather in its being a source book of differing points of view and rich examples, worth extended philosophical reflection. NEIL PICKERING Centre for the Study ofPhilosophy and Health Care, University College, Swansea. The values of psychotherapy Jeremy Holmes and Richard Lindley, ix + 256 pages, Oxford, Oxford University Press, £7.99 Inside an offputting black and white striped cover is a very solid, clear and intelligent book which argues the case for psychotherapy from the combined experience and perspectives of an analytic psychotherapist and a philos- opher. This is a useful book for those who want to know more about what distinguishes the different forms of psychotherapy (there is a clear description in the first chapter and the glossary at the end is helpful). It is also useful in dispelling many of the anti-psychotherapeutic myths and prejudices that still lurk in our culture, - providing a response to those who argue that psychotherapy 'promotes dependence', is an 'inter- minable', 'expensive' and 'elitist' form of treatment. It addresses all these issues and many more. It sees the promotion of emotional auton- omy as the core value of all psychotherapeutic treatment and from this perspective makes out a cogent case not simply for it to be made more widely available in the health service but for psychotherapy to be recognised as a necessary and integral part ofwhat the health service should provide for every citizen of a civilised democracy. In the first chapter the authors describe the task they have set them- selves in the first half of the book: 'We shall present a philosophical, ethical, technical, economic and political case for seeking a wide expansion of publicly funded psychotherapy'. First of all they pose the question 'What is psychotherapy?' and define it as 'the systematic use of a relationship between therapist and patient . . . to produce changes in cognition, feelings and behaviour'. They claim that the common ground or essential elements present in all psychotherapies are structure, space and relationship, and go on to classify the different therapies and their trainings with this in mind. I think it is in this area that the book runs into some difficulties. In order to make their case, they have to empha- sise the common ground between therapies and minimise the differ- ences. Not wanting to identify with what one might call the psychoana- lytic purism or elitism of parts of the psychoanalytic establishment, they have bent over backwards to take an eclectic and even-handed stance, implying that all forms of therapy have equal value and that the important thing is that the range and diversity is available. In effect, in many parts of the book, for example chapter 6, the book is arguing its case from the perspective and experience of analytic work so it is a little surprising that it doesn't make more explicit what is of particular value in applying psychoanalytic insight to the assessment and treat- ment of patients even if not in pure form. Is it really not of great impor- tance or significance that some train- ings do not require the trainees to undergo therapy themselves? Is the promotion of emotional autonomy of central and crucial significance to all different forms of therapy or do other values in some cases supersede this? The second chapter looks at the case against psychotherapy and ques- tions whether it is scientific and testable. It looks at arguments and counter-arguments in a coherent way and comes to the conclusion: 'It is extremely difficult to form a balanced, objective view of the scientific status of psychoanalysis and psychotherapy' and later on 'But is psychotherapy effective? This for most people is the decisive issue, rather than whether psychotherapy is strictly speaking a science, a pseudoscience, or perhaps o n A p ril 5 , 2 0 2 1 b y g u e st. P ro te cte d b y co p yrig h t. h ttp ://jm e .b m j.co m / J M e d E th ics: first p u b lish e d a s 1 0 .1 1 3 6 /jm e .1 9 .1 .5 9 -a o n 1 M a rch 1 9 9 3 . D o w n lo a d e d fro m http://jme.bmj.com/ work_i7bpgrh6lfgepmousgl7a6r37y ---- Munich Personal RePEc Archive Incentives and justice for sequencing problems. Mitra, Manipushpak and De, Parikshit Indian Statistical Institute, Kolkata March 2015 Online at https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/65447/ MPRA Paper No. 65447, posted 07 Jul 2015 04:24 UTC INCENTIVES AND JUSTICE FOR SEQUENCING PROBLEMS PARIKSHIT DE AND MANIPUSHPAK MITRA ABSTRACT. We address the mechanism design issue for the sequencing problem. We identify the just sequencing rule that serves the agents in the non-increasing order of their waiting costs and prove that it is a Rawlsian rule. We identify all rVCG mech- anisms that implement the just sequencing rule. The other properties of the just se- quencing rule that we identify are the following. It is an affine cost minimizer. It can be implemented with budget balanced rVCG mechanisms. Finally, when waiting cost and processing time are private information, we identify all generalized rVCG mechanisms that ex-post implement the just sequencing rule. JEL Classifications: C72, D63, D82. Keywords: sequencing, implementation, outcome efficient sequencing rule, just se- quencing rule, budget balance, ex-post implementation. 1. INTRODUCTION In this paper we address the mechanism design issue for the sequencing problem where agents have quasi-linear preferences. The setting comprises of a finite set of agents each of whom has one job to process using one facility. The facility can only handle one job at a time. No job can be interrupted once it starts processing. Each job is characterized by processing time and waiting cost. The latter represents the agent’s disutility for waiting one unit of time. There is a well established literature in this direction (see Dolan [10], Duives, Heydenreich, Mishra, Muller and Uetz [11], Hain and Mitra [13], Mitra [25], Moulin [27] and Suijs [33]). A well-known and well studied concept is the outcome efficient sequencing rule that minimizes the aggregate job completion cost of the agents. Outcome efficiency, as pointed out by Smith [32], requires that the jobs of the agents are processed in the non-increasing order of their urgency index where urgency index of any agent as the ratio of his waiting cost and his processing time. It is well-known that, as long as preferences are ‘smoothly connected’ (see Holmström [15]), outcome efficienct rules The authors would like to thank Debasis Mishra, Suresh Mutuswami and Arunava Sen for helpful com- ments and suggestions. 1 2 PARIKSHIT DE AND MANIPUSHPAK MITRA can be implemented in dominant strategies if and only if the mechanism is a Vickrey- Clarke-Groves (VCG) mechanism (see Clarke [8], Groves [12] and Vickrey [35]). For the sequencing problem outcome efficiency was analyzed by Dolan [10], Mitra [25] and Suijs [33]. The main contribution of this paper is to address the implementability issue of the Rawlsian sequencing rule which is based on John Rawls’ principle of distributive jus- tice (see Rawls [30]). The Rawlsian sequencing rule first identifies the maximum agent specific job completion cost for each order of serving and then picks that order which minimizes this maximum agent specific job completion cost. We show that a sequenc- ing rule for which agents are served in the non-increasing order of their waiting costs is a Rawlsian sequencing rule. We refer to this rule as the just sequencing rule and show that this Rawlsian rule is implementable in dominant strategies. We identify all ‘rVCG mechanisms’ that implements the just sequencing rule. Our result on implementation of the just sequencing rule shows compatibility of in- centives and justice. In the mechanism design literature without transfers where pref- erences of the agents are defined using distance from the bliss points, Chichilnisky and Heal [3] argued that Rawlsian rules are “locally dictatorial” and hence imple- mentable. However, in the mechanism design literature with transfers, this compat- ibility of incentives and justice is indeed rare. Papers by Deb and Mishra [9] and Lavi, Mu’alem and Nisan, N. [22] show that the Rawlsian allocation is incompatible with implementability in dominant strategies. To the best of our knowledge, the only other paper that shows this compatibility between incentives and justice is by Velez [34] for the (house) allocation problems.1 In the mechanism design literature a classic contribution is due to Roberts [31] who proved that, with unrestricted domains, if an allocation rule is implementable in dom- inant strategies, then it must be an ‘affine maximizer’ allocation rule. For the sequenc- ing problem the correct adoption of Roberts’ affine maximizer allocation rules is the ‘affine cost minimizer sequencing rules’. It is quite easy to verify that the outcome ef- ficient sequencing rule is an affine cost minimizer. Interestingly, the just sequencing rule, in spite of being a Rawlsian sequencing rule, is an affine cost minimizer. Consider the sequencing problem where the processing time of the agents are iden- tical. Such situations are referred to as the queueing problem. Queueing problems has been analyzed extensively from both normative and strategic viewpoints (see Chun [4], Chun, Mitra and Mutuswami [5], Hashimoto and Saitoh [14], Kayi and Ramaekars 1Velez [34] showed that the Generalized Money Rawlsian Fair solutions implements the no envy solu- tion in Nash and Strong Nash equilibria. INCENTIVES AND JUSTICE 3 [20], Maniquet [23], Mitra [24], Mitra and Mutuswami [29] and Mukherjee [28]). For the queueing problem, the outcome efficient sequencing rule implies that the rule is also the just sequencing rule. However, for sequencing problems with non-identical processing time across agents, outcome efficient sequencing rule is different from the just sequencing rule and hence such sequencing problems brings out the trade-off be- tween outcome efficient sequencing rule and the just sequencing rule. The importance of finding balanced VCG mechanisms to implement outcome effi- ciency for canonical allocation problems was highlighted by Zhou [37]. However, for many economic environments implementing outcome efficiency with balanced trans- fers is not possible (see Hurwicz [16], Hurwicz and Walker [17] and Walker [36]). For sequencing problem it is possible to get budget balanced (or first best) implementa- tion with the outcome efficiency (see Mitra[25] and Suijs [33]). We show that we can also find rVCG mechanisms that implements the just sequencing rule with balanced transfers and identify the set of all such balanced rVCG mechanisms. Again, for the queueing problem, the set of all balanced rVCG mechanisms coincide with the set of all balanced VCG mechanisms.2 The just sequencing rule is independent of the processing time of the agents. There- fore, if we have a two-dimensional incentive problem, where waiting cost and process- ing time are private information, ex-post implementability of the just sequencing rule is possible. If processing times are private information, we have mechanism design prob- lem under interdependent value, as the processing time generates interdependence across agents. Hence the correct notion of implementation is ex-post implementation. Specifically we show that the just sequencing rule is ex-post implementable by making some minor ‘modification’ in the rVCG mechanisms. Moreover, given the earlier re- sults on implementability of the just sequencing rule with balanced rVCG mechanisms, it follows that ex-post implementability with balanced transfers is also a possibility. Jehiel, Meyer-ter-Vehn, Moldovanu, and Zame [18] proved that the only determinis- tic social choice functions that are ex-post implementable in generic mechanism de- sign frameworks with multidimensional signals and interdependent valuations are those rules for which the same alternative is chosen irrespective of agents’ signals, that is, the outcome should be independent of the interdependent signals. In sequenc- ing with two-dimensional incentive problem, one dimension is waiting cost which is the private value and the other dimension is processing time that generates interde- pendence in terms of cost of completion time. The just sequencing rule is non-trivial 2The literature on balanced VCG mechanisms for the queueing problem includes paper like Chun , Mitra and Mutuswami [6], Kayi and Ramaekars [20] and Mitra [24]. 4 PARIKSHIT DE AND MANIPUSHPAK MITRA in terms of the waiting cost or private value dimension and is independent of the in- terdependence inducing processing time (like the independence of the interdependent signal required by Jehiel, Meyer-ter-Vehn, Moldovanu, and Zame [18] for ex-post im- plementability) and hence, the just sequencing rule is a non-trivial rule which is ex- post implementable. Moreover, for the outcome efficient sequencing rule the profile contingent order is dependent on the processing time and hence it is not ex-post im- plementable under this two-dimensional incentive problem.3 The paper is organized in the following way. In Section 2, we provide the framework of the sequencing problems. In Section 3, we introduce and analyze the just sequencing rule. In Section 4 we deal with properties of the just sequencing rule. This is followed by Section 5 which is the conclusion. 2. THE FRAMEWORK Consider a finite set of agents N = {1, 2, . . . , n} in need of a facility that can be used sequentially. Using this facility, the agents want to process their jobs. The job processing time can be different for different agents. Specifically, for each agent i ∈ N, the job processing time is given by si > 0. Let R++ be the positive orthant of the real line R and let θi Si measure the cost of job completion for agent i ∈ N where Si ∈ R++ is the job completion time for this agent and θi ∈ Θ := R++ denotes his constant per-period waiting cost. Due to the sequential nature of providing the service, the job completion time Si for agent i depends not only on his own processing time si but also on the processing time of the agents who precedes him in the order of service. By means of an order σ = (σ1, . . . , σn) on N, one can describe the positions of each agent in the order. Specifically, σi = k indicates that agent i has the k-th position in the order. Let Σ(N) be the set of n! possible orders on N. We define Pi(σ) = { j ∈ N \ {i} | σj < σi} to be the predecessor set of i in the order σ, that is, set of agents served before agent i in the order σ. Similarly, P′i (σ) = { j ∈ N \ {i} | σj > σi} denotes the successor set of i in the order σ, that is, set of agents served after agent i in the order σ. Let s = (s1, . . . , sn) ∈ S := R n ++ denote the vector of processing time of the agents. Given a vector s = (s1, . . . , sn) ∈ S and an order σ ∈ Σ(N), the cost of job completion for agent i ∈ N is θi Si(σ), where the job completion time is S j(σ) = ∑ j∈Pi(σ) s j + si. The agents have quasi-linear utility of the form vi(σ, τi ; mi = (θi , si); s−i) = −θi Si(σ) + τi where σ is the order, τi ∈ R is the transfer that he receives and the parameters of the 3Ex-post implementability literature includes papers by Bergemann and Morris [1], Bikhchandani [2], Chung and Ely [7], Jehiel, Meyer-ter-Vehn, Moldovanu and Zame [18], Jehiel and Moldovanu [19], and, Karsten, Kittsteiner, and Benny Moldovanu [21]). For the sequencing problem with private information only in processing time, incentive issues were addressed by Hain and Mitra [13] and Moulin [27]. INCENTIVES AND JUSTICE 5 model are agents own parameter mi = (θi , si) that constitutes of the waiting cost θi and the processing time si, and, more importantly, the processing time of the other agents that determines agent i’s job completion time Si(σ). Specifically, given a commonly known job processing time vector s = (s1, . . . , sn) ∈ S and an order σ ∈ Σ(N), the utility of agent i, with just the waiting cost parameter θi, reduces to vi(σ, τi ; mi = (θi , si); s−i) := Ui(σ, τi ; θi) = −θi Si(σ) + τi = −θi  si + ∑ j∈Pi(σ) s j   + τi . If we assume that both waiting cost and processing time are private information, then we have a general sequencing problem for N agents which we denote by ΩN = (Θ n, S). In this context we associate the utility function vi(.) for each i ∈ N. If the processing time vector s ∈ S is given and waiting cost is private information, then we have a sequencing problem ΩsN = (Θ n, s) and in that case the utility function reduces to Ui(.) (from vi(.)) for each i ∈ N. Except for Subsection 4.3, we will deal with Ω s N . Hence our first objective is to design direct revelation mechanisms for any given ΩsN . For any set X, let |X| denote the cardinality of X. A typical profile of waiting costs is denoted by θ = (θ1, . . . , θn) ∈ Θ n, and, for any i ∈ N, θ−i ∈ Θ |N\{i}| denotes the profile (θ1 . . . θi−1, θi+1, . . . θn) which is obtained from the profile θ by eliminating i’s waiting cost. For a given sequencing problem ΩsN , a (direct revelation) mechanism is (σ, τ) that constitutes of a sequencing rule σ and a transfer rule τ. A sequencing rule is a function σ : Θn → Σ(N) that specifies for each profile θ ∈ Θn a unique order σ(θ) = (σ1(θ), . . . , σn(θ)) ∈ Σ(N). 4 A transfer rule is a function τ : Θn → Rn that specifies for each profile θ ∈ Θn a transfer vector τ(θ) = (τi(θ), . . . , τn(θ)) ∈ R n. Specifically, given any sequencing problem ΩsN and given any mechanism (σ, τ), if (θ′i , θ−i) is the announced profile when the true waiting cost of i is θi, then utility of i is Ui(σ(θ ′ i , θ−i), τi(θ ′ i , θ−i); θi) = −θi Si(σ(θ ′ i , θ−i) + τi(θ ′ i , θ−i). Definition 1. A mechanism (σ, τ) implements the sequencing rule σ in dominant strate- gies if the transfer rule τ : Θn → Rn is such that for any i ∈ N, any θi , θ ′ i ∈ Θ and any θ−i ∈ Θ |N\{i}|, (1) Ui(σ(θ), τi(θ); θi) ≥ Ui(σ(θ ′ i , θ−i), τi(θ ′ i , θ−i); θi). 4The sequencing rule is a function and not a correspondence. Hence, we will require tie-breaking rule to reduce a correspondence to a function which, unless explicitly discussed, will be fixed. We use the following tie-breaking rule. We fix any linear order ≻ on the set of agents N. For any sequencing rule σ and any profile θ ∈ Θn with a tie situation between agents i, j ∈ N, we pick the order σ(θ) with σi(θ) < σj(θ) if and only if i ≻ j. 6 PARIKSHIT DE AND MANIPUSHPAK MITRA Implementation of a rule σ via a mechanism (σ, τ) requires that the transfer rule τ is such that truthful reporting for any agent weakly dominates false reporting irrespec- tive of other agents’ report. 2.1. The outcome efficient sequencing rule. Definition 2. A sequencing rule σ∗ is outcome efficient if for any θ ∈ Θn, σ∗(θ) ∈ argmin σ∈Σ(N) ∑i∈N θi Si(σ). For each profile the outcome efficient sequencing rule selects an order to minimiza- tion the aggregate cost of completion time. Define ui := θi/si as the urgency index of agent i which is the ratio of his waiting cost and his processing time. From Smith [32] we know that for any sequencing problem ΩsN a sequencing rule σ ∗ is outcome efficient if and only if for any profile θ, the selected order σ∗(θ) satisfies condition (OE): For any i, j ∈ N, θi/si ≥ θj/s j ⇔ σ ∗ i (θ) ≤ σ ∗ j (θ). 5 Therefore, outcome efficient sequencing rule requires that the agents are ordered in the non-increasing order of their urgency index. From (OE) it is clear that if θi/si ≥ θj/s j, then Si(σ ∗(θ)) ≤ S j(σ ∗(θ)). Consider the outcome efficient sequencing rule σ∗. It is well-known that VCG mechanisms are the only mechanisms that implement σ∗ (see Holmström [15]). Definition 3. For the outcome efficient sequencing rule σ∗, a mechanism (σ∗, τ) is a VCG mechanism if the transfer rule is such that for all θ ∈ Θn and all i ∈ N, (2) τ∗i (θ) =    hi(θ−i) if P ′ i (σ ∗(θ)) = ∅, hi(θ−i) − si ∑ j∈P′ i (σ∗(θ)) θj otherwise. where the function hi : Θ |N\{i}| → R is arbitrary. Given a sequencing problem ΩsN , for any profile θ ∈ Θ n and any i ∈ N and any j ∈ N \ {i}, let θjsi be the pivotal cost of agent i on agent j. We call this the pivotal cost because θjsi is the incremental cost that agent j has to incur if agent i precedes agent j in any order. The VCG transfer in condition (2) specifies that for any i ∈ N and any θ−i ∈ Θ N\{i}, if θi is such that agent i is served last in the outcome efficient order σ∗(θi , θ−i), that is, if P ′ i (σ ∗(θi , θ−i)) = ∅, then τ ∗ i (θi , θ−i) = hi(θ−i). If, however, θ ′ i is such that agent i is not served last in the order σ∗(θ′i , θ−i), that is, if P ′ i (σ ∗(θ′i , θ−i) 6= ∅, then agent i’s transfer τ∗i (θ ′ i , θ−i) not only has hi(θ−i) but he also has to pay the sum of the pivotal cost that agent i incurs on his followers in the order σ∗(θ′i , θ−i) (that is, the waiting cost of all the agent(s) served after him times his own processing time). 5Given the tie-breaking rule, this selection is unique. INCENTIVES AND JUSTICE 7 The VCG transfer τ∗i (θ) (in condition (2)) for which the agent specific constant func- tions hi(.) are always zero for all agents gives us the pivotal mechanism for implement- ing the outcome efficient order σ∗. The first work that identified the pivotal mechanism for any sequencing problem is by Dolan [10]. It must be pointed out that the specifica- tion (2) of the VCG transfers is the pivotal based representation of the VCG transfers and is not its standard representation. We show that an appropriate transformation of the standard VCG transfers gives us (2). The standard way of specifying the VCG transfers is that for all θ and for all i ∈ N, (3) τ∗i (θ) = − ∑ j∈N\{i} S j(σ ∗(θ))θj + gi(θ−i). 6 Consider the outcome efficient order σ∗(θ) for the profile θ ∈ Θn and suppose that agent i leaves. We define the “induced” order σ∗(θ−i) (of length |N \ {i}|) for the agents in N \ {i} as follows: (4) σ∗j (θ−i) = { σ∗j (θ) − 1 if j ∈ P ′ i (σ ∗(θ)), σ∗j (θ) if j ∈ Pi(σ ∗(θ)). In words, σ∗(θ−i) is the order formed by removing agent i and moving all agents be- hind him up by one position. Given the same tie-breaking rule for the economy with N \ {i} agents, it is easy to see that if σ∗(θ) is outcome efficient for the profile θ, then σ∗(θ−i) is also outcome efficient in N \ {i} for the profile θ−i. Without loss of general- ity, we can write for all θ and all i ∈ N, (A) gi(θ−i) = ∑ j∈N\{i} S j(σ ∗(θ−i))θj + hi(θ−i). By substituting (A) in (3) we get (5) τ∗i (θ) = − ∑ j∈N\{i} [S j(σ ∗(θ)) − S j(σ ∗(θ−i))]θj + hi(θ−i). If for a profile θ ∈ Θn, the outcome efficient order is σ∗(θ) and agent i leaves, then the order σ∗(θ−i) is such that if j ∈ Pi(σ ∗(θ)), then j’s completion time remains unaltered and if k ∈ P′i (σ ∗(θ)), then k’s completion time reduces by si. Hence (6) S j(σ ∗(θ)) − S j(σ ∗(θ−i)) = { si if j ∈ P ′ i (σ ∗(θ)), 0 if j ∈ Pi(σ ∗(θ)). By substituting condition (6) in the transformed VCG transfer (5) and then simplifying it we get the VCG transfer (2).7 6See Mitra [25] and Suijs [33]. 7A similar argument for the pivotal based representation of VCG transfers (like condition (2)) for the queueing problem can be found in Chun, Mitra and Mutuswami [5]. 8 PARIKSHIT DE AND MANIPUSHPAK MITRA 3. AN IMPLEMENTABLE RAWLSIAN SEQUENCING RULE Definition 4. A sequencing rule σ′ is Rawlsian if for each profile θ ∈ Θn, σ′(θ) ∈ min σ∈Σ(N) max j∈N S j(σ)θj. Given any profile θ ∈ Θn, for each order σ ∈ Σ(N), let M(σ) = θj S j(σ) ≥ θk Sk(σ) for all k ∈ N, that is, for the given profile θ and given the order σ, M(σ) is the maximum value of the cost of completion time among all agents in N. The Rawlsian sequencing rule picks that order σ′ ∈ Σ(N) for which M(σ′) is minimum, that is M(σ′) ≤ M(σ) for all σ ∈ Σ(N). Example 1. Consider the sequencing problem ΩsN such that N = {1, 2, 3} and s = (s1 = 1, s2 = 2, s3 = 3). Let the waiting cost vector be θ = (θ1 = 100, θ2 = 5, θ3 = 3). For θ, outcome efficiency uniquely picks the order σ1 = (σ1 = 1, σ2 = 2, σ3 = 3) since u1 > u2 > u2. However, the Rawlsian selection is not unique. For profile θ we have the following: M(σ1 = (σ1 = 1, σ2 = 2, σ3 = 3)) = θ1s1 = 100, M(σ 2 = (σ1 = 1, σ2 = 3, σ3 = 2)) = θ1s1 = 100, M(σ 3 = (σ1 = 2, σ2 = 1, σ3 = 3)) = θ1(s2 + s1) = 300, M(σ4 = (σ1 = 2, σ2 = 3, σ3 = 1)) = θ1(s3 + s1) = 400, M(σ 5 = (σ1 = 3, σ2 = 1, σ3 = 2)) = θ1(s2 + s3 + s1) = 600, and M(σ 6 = (σ1 = 3, σ2 = 2, σ3 = 1)) = θ1(s3 + s2 + s1) = 600. Therefore, for the profile θ, the Rawlsian rule can either pick σ1 or σ2 implying that the Rawlsian rule does not guarantee state contingent unique order selection. Note that the order σ1 also has the property that it serves the agents in the decreasing (hence non-increasing) order of their waiting cost, that is given θ1 > θ2 > θ3, agent 1 is served first followed by agent 2 and then by agent 3. Let the waiting cost vector be θ′ = (θ′1 = 10, θ2 = 5, θ3 = 3). For profile θ ′ we have the following: M(σ1 = (σ1 = 1, σ2 = 2, σ3 = 3)) = θ3(s1 + s2 + s3) = 18, M(σ2 = (σ1 = 1, σ2 = 3, σ3 = 2)) = θ2(s1 + s3 + s2) = 30, M(σ 3 = (σ1 = 2, σ2 = 1, σ3 = 3)) = θ ′ 1(s2 + s1) = 30, M(σ 4 = (σ1 = 2, σ2 = 3, σ3 = 1)) = θ ′ 1(s3 + s1) = 40, M(σ5 = (σ1 = 3, σ2 = 1, σ3 = 2)) = θ ′ 1(s2 + s3 + s1) = 60, and M(σ 6 = (σ1 = 3, σ2 = 2, σ3 = 1)) = θ ′ 1(s3 + s2 + s1) = 60. For the profile θ ′, M(σ1) < M(σk) for all k ∈ {2, . . . , 6} and hence any Rawlsian rule uniquely picks σ1. The above example suggests that we can have profiles θ for which more than one order is Rawlsian. It also seems likely that serving the agents in the non-increasing order of their waiting costs is always Rawlsian. In the next theorem we show that this is indeed the case. INCENTIVES AND JUSTICE 9 Definition 5. A sequencing rule σ̃ is just if for each profile θ ∈ Θn, the chosen order σ̃(θ) satisfies the following property: for any i, j ∈ N such that θi ≥ θj, σ̃i(θ) ≤ σ̃j(θ). 8 Theorem 1. For any ΩsN , the just sequencing rule σ̃ is Rawlsian. Proof: To prove that the just sequencing rule σ̃ is Rawlsian, consider any profile θ ∈ Θn and the just order σ̃(θ). Consider that agent i ∈ N for whom the cost of completion time θi Si(σ̃(θ)) = θi(∑ j∈Pi(σ̃(θ)) s j + si) is maximum under σ̃(θ), that is M(σ̃(θ)) = θi Si(σ̃(θ)). 9 Define O := Pi(σ̃(θ)) ∪ {i} as the set that includes the set of predecessors of i under the order σ̃(θ) and that also includes agent i. Observe that from the defini- tion of just sequencing rule it follows that θj ≥ θi for all j ∈ O. Consider any other order σ ∈ Σ(N) \ {σ̃(θ)}. For this order σ, there is one agent in O who will be served last under σ relative to the other members of O, that is, there exists an agent j ∈ O such that σj > σk for all k ∈ O \ { j}. This means that O ⊆ Pj(σ) ∪ { j}, and hence S j(σ) ≥ Si(σ̃(θ)), that is the completion time of agent j under the order σ is not less than the completion time of agent i under the order σ̃(θ). Therefore, the maximum cost of completion time M(σ) under σ is at least as large as the maximum cost of com- pletion time M(σ̃(θ)) = θi Si(σ̃(θ)) under σ̃(θ) since M(σ) ≥ θj S j(σ) ≥ θj Si(σ̃(θ)) ≥ θi Si(σ̃(θ)) = M(σ̃(θ)). Since the selection of σ was arbitrary the result follows. � Remark 1. Consider any sequencing problem Ωs ∗ N with s ∗ = (s∗1 , . . . , s ∗ n) ∈ S and s∗1 = . . . = s ∗ n so that we have the queueing problem. Then the outcome efficient sequencing rule implies the just sequencing rule and hence a Rawlsian sequencing rule. For the queueing problem Ωs ∗ N , for any profile θ ∈ Θ n, the order of the urgency indexes and that of the waiting costs are identical and hence this implication. Definition 6. For the just sequencing rule σ̃, a mechanism (σ̃, τ̃) is an rVCG mechanism if the transfer rule is such that for all θ ∈ Θn and all i ∈ N, (7) τ̃i(θ) =    hi(θ−i) if P ′ i (σ̃(θ)) = ∅, hi(θ−i) − ∑ j∈P′ i (σ̃(θ)) θjs j otherwise. where the function hi : Θ |N\{i}| → R is arbitrary. Given a sequencing problem ΩsN , for any profile θ ∈ Θ n and any j ∈ N, let θjs j be the minimum cost of agent j, that is the cost that agent j would have incurred if he was served first in any order. Like the VCG transfers (2), the rVCG transfers (7) 8Given the tie-breaking rule, for any profile θ ∈ Θn, this selection σ̃(θ) is unique. 9If there are more than one agent for whom the cost is maximum, pick any one of them arbitrarily. 10 PARIKSHIT DE AND MANIPUSHPAK MITRA specifies that for any i ∈ N and any θ−i ∈ Θ N\{i}, if θi is such that agent i is served last in the just order σ̃(θi , θ−i), then τ̃i(θi , θ−i) = hi(θ−i). If θ ′ i is such that agent i is not served last in the order σ̃(θ′i , θ−i), then agent i’s transfer τ̃i(θ ′ i , θ−i) not only has hi(θ−i) but he also has to pay the sum of the minimum cost of his followers in the just order σ̃(θ′i , θ−i). As long as we are in a sequencing problem Ω s N where the processing time of the agents are not identical, there will be some profile θ and some agent j for whom the minimum cost θjs j will be different from the pivotal cost θjsi of i on j for some i ∈ N \ { j}. Hence the payment amounts in the rVCG transfers are qualitatively different from the payment amounts under the VCG transfers (2) where, recall that, the payment amount is the sum of the pivotal cost of agent i on all his followers in the outcome efficient sequencing order. Therefore, it is easy to see that for the queueing problem Ωs ∗ N we have the following: For any agent j ∈ N, any agent i ∈ N \ {i} and any profile θ, the minimum cost θjs ∗ j is identical to the pivotal cost θjs ∗ i since s ∗ i = s ∗ j and, given the same tie-breaking rule, σ∗(θ) = σ̃(θ). Thus, the VCG-mechanisms and the rVCG mechanisms are identical for the queueing problem Ωs ∗ N . Theorem 2. The just sequencing rule σ̃ is implementable if and only if the mechanism (σ̃, τ) that implements it is an rVCG mechanism. Proof: Consider the just sequencing rule σ̃. We first prove that if a mechanism (σ̃, τ) implements σ̃, then it is necessarily the rVCG mechanism. Consider any agent i ∈ N and fix any profile θ−i ∈ Θ |N\{i}| of all but agent i. By taking any two types θi and θ ′ i for agent i and applying the two implementation inequalities (1) Ui(σ̃(θ), τi(θ); θi) ≥ Ui(σ̃(θ ′ i , θ−i), τi(θ ′ i , θ−i); θi) and (2) Ui(σ̃(θ), τi(θ); θ ′ i) ≤ Ui(σ̃(θ ′ i , θ−i), τi(θ ′ i , θ−i); θ ′ i). In general, from inequalities (1) and (2) we get (8) [Si(σ̃(θ ′ i , θi )) − Si(σ̃(θ))]θi ≥ τi(θ ′ i , θ−i) − τi(θ) ≥ [Si(σ̃(θ ′ i , θi )) − Si(σ̃(θ))]θ ′ i . If θi and θ ′ i are such that σ̃(θ) = σ̃(θ ′ i , θ−i), then Si(σ̃(θ ′ i , θi )) = Si(σ̃(θ)) and inequal- ity (8) gives τi(θ) = τi(θ ′ i , θ−i). Let θ(1) ≥ θ(2) ≥ . . . ≥ θ(n−1) be the decreasing order of the waiting cost for the fixed profile θ−i. Consider any pair (θ t+1 i , θti ) ∈ [θ(t+1), θ(t)] × [θ(t), θ(t−1)]. Using the just sequencing rule σ̃ and applying the implementability condition (8) when the actual profile is (θt+1 i , θ−i) ((θ t i , θ−i)) and the misreport of agent i is θ t i (θ t+1 i ) we get (9) θt+1 i s(t) ≤ τi(θ t+1 i , θ−i) − τi(θ t i , θ−i) ≤ θ t i s(t). Since (9) must hold for all (θt+1 i , θti ) ∈ [θ (t+1) i , θ (t) i ] × [θ (t) i , θ (t−1) i ], it follows that (10) τi(θ t+1 i , θ−i) − τi(θ t i , θ−i) = θ(t)s(t). INCENTIVES AND JUSTICE 11 Condition (10) must hold for all t ∈ {1, . . . , n − 1}. By setting τi(θ n i , θ−i) = hi(θ−i) for any θni ∈ (0, θ(n−1)) and then solving condition (10) recursively we get the rVCG transfers (7). For the converse consider any agent i ∈ N and any profile θ−i. Let θi be the true wait- ing cost of i and Bi(θ ′ i ; θi) := Ui(σ̃(θ ′ i , θ−i), τi(θ ′ i , θ−i); θi) − Ui(σ̃(θi , θ−i), τi(θi , θ−i); θi) be the benefit of agent i from a misreport θ′i . (D1) If θ′i > θi and Pi(σ̃(θi , θ−i)) \ Pi(σ̃(θ ′ i , θ−i)) 6= ∅, then from the just sequencing rule we get θj ≥ θi for all j ∈ Pi(σ̃(θi , θ−i)) \ Pi(σ̃(θ ′ i , θ−i)). Therefore, using any rVCG transfer we get Bi(θ ′ i ; θi) = ∑ j∈Pi(σ̃(θi ,θ−i))\Pi(σ̃(θ′i ,θ−i)) (θi −θj)s j ≤ 0. (D2) If θ′i < θi and Pi(σ̃(θ ′ i , θ−i)) \ Pi(σ̃(θi , θ−i)) 6= ∅, then from the just sequencing rule we get θj ≤ θi for all j ∈ Pi(σ̃(θ ′ i , θ−i)) \ Pi(σ̃(θi , θ−i)). Hence using any rVCG transfer we get Bi(θ ′ i ; θi) = ∑ j∈Pi(σ̃(θ′i ,θ−i))\Pi(σ̃(θi ,θ−i)) (θj −θi)s j ≤ 0. (D3) Finally, if θ′i 6= θi and Pi(σ̃(θ ′ i , θ−i)) = Pi(σ̃(θi , θ−i)), then Bi(θ ′ i ; θi) = 0. Therefore, cases (D1)-(D3) show that agent i cannot benefit from any deviation. Since the selection of agent i was arbitrary, the result follows. � 4. PROPERTIES OF THE JUST SEQUENCING RULE In this section we focus on three nice properties of the just sequencing rule. 4.1. The just sequencing rule as an affine cost minimizer. Roberts [31] defined affine maximizer allocation rules in a general mechanism design framework with quasi- linear preferences. However, sequencing problems are cost problems and hence the appropriate adoption of affine maximizer allocation rule of Roberts to the sequencing problem is the ‘affine cost minimizer sequencing rules’. Definition 7. A sequencing rule σw,κ : Θn → Σ(N) is an affine cost minimizer if for each θ ∈ Θn, σw,κ(θ) ∈ arg minσ∈Σ(N) { κ(σ) + ∑ j∈N w jθj S j(σ) } , where w j ≥ 0 for all j ∈ N with at least one w j > 0 and the function κ : Σ(N) → R is arbitrary. The affine maximizer sequencing rule σ1,0 with κ(σ) = 0 for all σ ∈ Σ(N) and w j = 1 for all j ∈ N gives the outcome efficient sequencing rule, that is σ 1,0 = σ∗.10 Thus, the outcome efficient sequencing rule is a affine cost minimizer. Proposition 1. The just sequencing rule σ̃ is an affine cost maximizer. 10The equality σ1,0 = σ∗ is with the implicit assumption that the tie-breaking rule followed to obtain σ1,0 is identical to the tie-breaking rule of σ∗. 12 PARIKSHIT DE AND MANIPUSHPAK MITRA Proof: To prove that the just sequencing rule is a affine cost minimizer, we show that the affine cost minimizer sequencing rule σw ∗,0 with κ(σ) = 0 for all σ ∈ Σ(N) and w∗j = 1/(∏r 6= j sr) > 0 for all j ∈ N coincides with the just sequencing rule σ̃. Consider any profile θ ∈ Θn and any two agents i, j ∈ N with θi ≥ θj. Consider any order σ such that k = σj = σi + 1 for any given k ∈ {1, . . . , n − 1}. Given our objective is to minimize ∑ j∈N w ∗ jθj S j(σ), the sum of weighted completion costs of i and j for σ is (11) Ci j(σ) := w ∗ i θi Si(σ) + w ∗ jθj S j(σ) = θi ( si + ∑k∈Pi(σ) sk ∏r 6=i sr ) +θj ( si + s j + ∑k∈Pi(σ) sk ∏r 6= j sr ) . Consider the order σ′ obtained from σ by interchanging the positions of i and j only, that is σ′j = σi , σ ′ i = σj and σ ′ k = σk for all k ∈ N \ {i, j}. The sum of weighted completion costs of i and j for σ′ is (12) Ci j(σ ′) := w∗i θi Si(σ ′) + w∗jθj S j(σ ′) = θi ( si + s j ∑k∈Pi(σ) sk ∏r 6=i sr ) +θj ( s j + ∑k∈Pi(σ) sk ∏r 6= j sr ) . By taking the difference Ci j(σ ′) − Ci j(σ) and using conditions (11) and (12) and making some obvious simplifications we get (13) Ci j(σ ′) − Ci j(σ) = (θi −θj) ( 1 ∏r∈N\{i, j} sr ) ≥ 0. In condition (13), the inequality is strict if θi > θj. Condition (13) shows that if θi ≥ θj, then for any two consecutive positions in an order it is not more costly to serve agents i before agent j and if θi > θj, then it is less costly to serve agent i before agent j. Notice that for this conclusion we neither required the profile of waiting costs of the agents N \ {i, j} nor did we require the positions of the agent N \ {i, j} in the order. Hence, if for any profile θ ∈ Θn, our objective is to select σw ∗,0(θ) ∈ arg minσ∈Σ(N) { ∑ j∈N w ∗ jθj S j(σ) } , then σw ∗,0(θ) must follow the following property: (Aff) For any i, j ∈ N such that θi ≥ θj, σ w∗,0 i (θ) ≤ σ w∗,0 j (θ). Moreover, since N \ {i, j} did not matter in condition (13), the converse is also true, that is, given any profile θ, condition (Aff) gives σw ∗,0(θ) ∈ arg minσ∈Σ(N) { ∑ j∈N w ∗ jθj S j(σ) } . Given the tie breaking rule, the order obtained by following condition (Aff) is the same as the order obtained from the just sequencing rule σ̃. Hence the result follows. � Remark 2. In general, for any affine cost minimizer sequencing rule σw,κ̄ with the prop- erty that κ(σ) = κ̄ for all σ ∈ Σ(N), urgency index can be replaced by weighted INCENTIVES AND JUSTICE 13 urgency index uwi = (wiθi)/si to determine the profile contingent order of serving the agents. Specifically, like Smith’s [32] rule for outcome efficiency, for these affine cost minimizers σw,κ̄, σw,κ̄(θ) affine cost minimizes {κ̄ + ∑ j∈N w jθj S j(σ)} if and only if the selected order σw,κ̄(θ) satisfies condition (ACM): For any i, j ∈ N, (wiθi)/si ≥ (w jθj)/s j ⇔ σ w,κ̄ i (θ) ≤ σw,κ̄ j (θ).11 More importantly, the affine cost minimizer se- quencing rule σw ∗,0 that gives the just sequencing rule σ̃ has w∗j = (1/ ∏k∈N\{ j} sk) as the agent specific weights and hence weighted urgency index is uw ∗ i = (θi/ ∏k∈N sk). Therefore, for any θ ∈ Θn and any i, j ∈ N, uw ∗ i ≥ u w∗ j if and only if θi ≥ θj. That is, for the affine cost minimizer sequencing rule σw ∗,0 that gives σ̃, comparison of weighted urgency index across agents reduces to the comparison of the waiting costs across agents. 4.2. Budget balanced implementability of the just sequencing rule. For implemen- tation of outcome efficient allocation rules, Zhou [37] provided examples of both public and private good allocation problems for which no budget balancing VCG mechanisms exists and for which all VCG mechanisms are inferior to other ‘reasonable’ non-VCG mechanisms. Zhou [37] concluded that unless one can find a budget balancing VCG mechanism, one should limit its use. Implementation of outcome efficient rules with balanced transfers is difficult to get in many economic environments (see, for example, Hurwicz and Walker [17] and Walker [36]). That implementation of outcome efficiency is possible with balanced transfers for sequencing and queueing problems was estab- lished by Mitra [24], [25] and Suijs [33]. Mitra and Sen [26] characterized domains in a heterogenous objects model with private values where an outcome efficient rule can be implemented in dominant strategies with balanced transfers. They show that these domains are non-trivial and are ‘closely’ related to incentive problems in sequencing and queueing problems studied in Mitra [24], [25] and Suijs [33]. We prove that for sequencing problems, if we replace outcome efficient sequencing rule with the just se- quencing rule, we get implementability with balanced transfers provided there are at least three agents. Definition 8. A sequencing rule σ is implementable with balanced transfers if the mech- anism (σ, τ) that implements it has a budget balanced transfer, that is, for all θ ∈ Θn, ∑ j∈N τj(θ) = 0. Proposition 2. For any sequencing problem Ω (s1 ,s2) N={1,2} with two agents, implementa- tion of the just sequencing rule σ̃ with balanced transfers is not possible. 11Given the tie-breaking rule, this profile contingent selection σw,κ(θ) is unique. 14 PARIKSHIT DE AND MANIPUSHPAK MITRA Proof: Fix any processing time vector (s1, s2) and consider the sequencing problem Ω s N={1,2} . To implement the refined sequencing rule it is necessary that the mechanism (σ, τ) is an rVCG mechanism (Theorem 2). Pick any rVCG mechanism. Consider the waiting costs θ1, θ ′ 1, θ2, θ ′ 2 such that θ1 > θ ′ 2 > θ ′ 1 > θ2 and θ ′ 1s1 6= θ ′ 2s2. Budget balance for the profile (θ1, θ2) gives (B1) h1(θ2) + h2(θ1) − θ2s2 = 0. Budget balance for (θ1, θ ′ 2) gives (B2) h1(θ ′ 2) + h2(θ1) −θ ′ 2s2 = 0. Budget balance for (θ ′ 1, θ2) gives (B3) h1(θ2) + h2(θ ′ 1) − θ2s2 = 0. Finally, budget balance for the profile (θ ′ 1, θ ′ 2) gives (B4) h1(θ ′ 2) + h2(θ ′ 1) −θ ′ 1s1 = 0. By adding (B1) and (B4) and subtracting both (B2) and (B3) from it we get θ′2s2 −θ ′ 1s1 = 0 which contradicts the restriction that θ ′ 1s1 6= θ ′ 2s2. � Definition 9. Consider any ΩsN with at least three agents. A mechanism (σ̃, τ̃ ∗) is a balanced rVCG mechanism if the transfer rule is such that for all θ ∈ Θn and all i ∈ N, (14) τ̃ ∗ i (θ) =                ∑ j∈N\{i} ( σ̃j(θ)−1 n−2 ) θjs j + gi(θ−i) if P ′ i (σ̃(θ)) = ∅, − ∑ j∈N\{i} ( n−σ̃j(θ) n−2 ) θjs j + gi(θ−i) if Pi(σ̃(θ)) = ∅, ∑ j∈Pi(σ̃(θ)) ( σ̃j(θ)−1 n−2 ) θjs j − ∑ j∈P′ i (σ̃(θ)) ( n−σ̃j(θ) n−2 ) θjs j + gi(θ−i) otherwise. where gi : Θ |N\{i}| → R for each i ∈ N is such that for any θ ∈ Θn, ∑i∈N gi(θ−i) = 0. The balanced rVCG transfer requires that for any profile θ ∈ Θn and given any agent specific constant transfer gi(θ−i) to agent i, each agent i, in addition, receives as reward a position specific weighted sum of the minimum cost of all agents served before him (∑ j∈Pi(σ̃(θ))[(σ̃j(θ) − 1)/(n − 2)]θjs j) under the refined Ralwsian sequencing order σ̃(θ) (provided Pi(σ̃(θ)) 6= ∅) and agent i also pays a position specific weighted sum of the minimum cost of all agents served after him (∑ j∈P′ i (σ̃(θ))[(n −σ̃j(θ))/(n − 2)]θjs j) under the refined Ralwsian sequencing order σ̃(θ) (provided P′i (σ̃(θ)) 6= ∅). In addition, the balanced rVCG mechanism also requires that selection of the function gi : Θ |N\{i}| → R for each agent i ∈ N must be such that for any θ ∈ Θn, ∑ j∈N g j(θ− j) = 0. Theorem 3. Let ΩsN be a sequencing problem with at least three agents. The just se- quencing rule is implementable with balanced transfers if and only if the mechanism (σ̃, τ) that implements it is a balanced rVCG mechanism. Proof: We know that the just sequencing rule is implementable if and only if the mech- anism is an rVCG mechanism (Theorem 2). Therefore, identifying the complete class of INCENTIVES AND JUSTICE 15 mechanisms that implements the just sequencing rule with balanced transfers reduces to identifying the complete class of balanced rVCG mechanisms. Suppose there is the refined Ralwsian order σ̃(θ) for the profile θ ∈ Θn and agent i leaves. We define the “induced” order σ̃(θ−i) (of length |N \ {i}|) for the agents in N \ {i} as follows: (15) σ̃j(θ−i) = { σ̃j(θ) − 1 if j ∈ P ′ i (σ̃(θ)), σ̃j(θ) if j ∈ Pi(σ̃(θ)). In words, σ̃(θ−i) is the order formed by removing agent i and moving all agents behind him up by one position. Given the same tie-breaking rule for the economy with N \ {i} agents, it is easy to see that σ̃(θ−i) is also just in N \ {i} for the profile θ−i if σ̃(θ) is just for the profile θ. Given that the sequencing problem ΩsN has at least three agents, without loss of generality, we redefine the rVCG mechanisms by setting for each agent i ∈ N and each profile θ−i, (16) hi(θ−i) = ∑ j∈N\{i} ( σ̃j(θ−i) − 1 n − 2 ) θjs j + gi(θ−i), where gi : Θ |N\{i}| → R is arbitrary. By substituting (16) in the rVCG transfer (7) we get the following for any i ∈ N and any θ ∈ Θn. (A) If P′i (σ̃(θ)) = ∅, then σ̃j(θ−i) = σ̃j(θ) for all j ∈ N \ {i} and from (7) we get τ̃i(θ) = hi(θ−i) = ∑ j∈N\{i} ( σ̃j(θ)−1 n−2 ) θjs j + gi(θ−i). (B) If Pi(σ̃(θ)) = ∅, then σ̃j(θ−i) = σ̃j(θ) − 1 for all j ∈ N \ {i} and from (7) we get τ̃i(θ) = − ∑ j∈N\{i} θjs j + hi(θ−i) = − ∑ j∈N\{i} θjs j + ∑ j∈N\{i} ( σ̃j(θ)−2 n−2 ) θjs j + gi(θ−i) = − ∑ j∈N\{i} ( n−σ̃j(θ) n−2 ) θjs j + gi(θ−i). (C) If P′i (σ̃(θ)) 6= ∅ and Pi(σ̃(θ)) 6= ∅, then σ̃j(θ−i) = σ̃j(θ) for all j ∈ Pi(σ̃(θ)) 6= ∅, σ̃j(θ−i) = σ̃j(θ) − 1 for all j ∈ P ′ i (σ̃(θ)) 6= ∅ and from (7) we get τ̃i(θ) = − ∑ j∈P′ i (σ̃(θ)) θjs j + hi(θ−i) = − ∑ j∈P′ i (σ̃(θ)) θjs j + ∑ j∈Pi(σ̃(θ)) ( σ̃j(θ)−1 n−2 ) θjs j + ∑ j∈P′ i (σ̃(θ)) ( σ̃j(θ)−2 n−2 ) θjs j + gi(θ−i) = ∑ j∈Pi(σ̃(θ)) ( σ̃j(θ)−1 n−2 ) θjs j − ∑ j∈P′ i (σ̃(θ)) ( n−σ̃j(θ) n−2 ) θjs j + gi(θ−i). Conditions (A)-(C) show that when the sequencing problem ΩsN has at least three agents, then an equivalent representation of the rVCG transfers is that for any i ∈ N and any θ ∈ Θn, 16 PARIKSHIT DE AND MANIPUSHPAK MITRA (17) τ̃ ′ i (θ) =                ∑ j∈N\{i} ( σ̃j(θ)−1 n−2 ) θjs j + gi(θ−i) if P ′ i (σ̃(θ)) = ∅, − ∑ j∈N\{i} ( n−σ̃j(θ) n−2 ) θjs j + gi(θ−i) if Pi(σ̃(θ)) = ∅, ∑ j∈Pi(σ̃(θ)) ( σ̃j(θ)−1 n−2 ) θjs j − ∑ j∈P′ i (σ̃(θ)) ( n−σ̃j(θ) n−2 ) θjs j + gi(θ−i) otherwise, where for each i ∈ N, the function gi : Θ |N\{i}| → R is arbitrary. By taking the repre- sentation (17) of the rVCG transfer we get for any θ ∈ Θn, ∑ k∈N τ̃′ k (θ) = ∑ k∈N { ∑ j∈Pk(σ̃(θ)) ( σ̃j(θ)−1 n−2 ) θjs j − ∑ j∈P′ k (σ̃(θ)) ( n−σ̃j(θ) n−2 ) θjs j } + ∑ k∈N gk(θ−k) = ∑ k∈N ∑ j∈Pk(σ̃(θ)) ( σ̃j(θ)−1 n−2 ) θjs j − ∑ k∈N ∑ j∈P′ k (σ̃(θ)) ( n−σ̃j(θ) n−2 ) θjs j + ∑ k∈N gk(θ−k) = ∑ j∈N { |P′j(σ̃j(θ))| ( σ̃j(θ)−1 n−2 )} θjs j − ∑ j∈N { |Pj(σ̃j(θ))| ( n−σ̃j(θ) n−2 )} θjs j + ∑ k∈N gk(θ−k) = ∑ j∈N { (n −σ̃j(θ)) ( σ̃j(θ)−1 n−2 )} θjs j − ∑ j∈N { (σ̃j(θ) − 1) ( n−σ̃j(θ) n−2 )} θjs j + ∑ k∈N gk(θ−k) = ∑ k∈N gk(θ−k). Therefore, by taking the representation (17) of the rVCG transfer we have proved that for any θ ∈ Θn, ∑ k∈N τ̃′ k (θ) = ∑ k∈N gk(θ−k). Therefore, an rVCG mechanism repre- sented by (17) is budget balanced if and only if (I) for all θ ∈ Θn, ∑ k∈N gk(θ−k) = 0. From the representation (17) of the rVCG transfers and from condition (I), the result follows. � Remark 3. There are papers that show that for the family of sequencing problems ΩsN with three or more agents we can find budget balanced VCG mechanisms and hence implementation with balanced transfer is also possible with the outcome efficient se- quencing rule (see Mitra [25] and Suijs [33]). From Remark 1 it follows that for the queueing problem Ωs ∗ N , the set of all balanced rVCG mechanism coincides with the set of all VCG mechanisms that first best implements the outcome efficient sequencing rule. 4.3. Two-dimensional incentives and the just sequencing rule. If we assume that both waiting cost and the processing time are agent specific private information, then we have the mechanism design problem for the general sequencing problem ΩN = INCENTIVES AND JUSTICE 17 (Θn, S). Specifically, we have an interdependent value situation and therefore the cor- rect notion is ex-post implementability. The type of any agent i ∈ N is mi = (θi , si) ∈ Θ × R++ that constitutes of his waiting cost as well as his processing time. A pro- file is m = (m1, . . . , mn) ∈ Θ n × S. For any i ∈ N, let m−i, denote the profile (m1, . . . , mi−1, mi+1, . . . , mn) ∈ Θ |N\{i}| × R |N\{i}| ++ which is obtained from the profile m by eliminating i’s type. For the general sequencing problem ΩN , a (direct reve- lation) mechanism is (σ g, τ) that constitutes of a general sequencing rule σ g and a transfer rule τ. A general sequencing rule is a function σ g : Θn × S → Σ(N) that spec- ifies for each profile m ∈ Θn × S, a unique order σ g(m) = (σ g 1 (m), . . . , σ g n (m)) ∈ Σ(N). A transfer rule is a function τ : Θn × S → Rn that specifies for each profile m ∈ Θn × S a transfer vector τ(m) = (τ1(m), . . . , τn(m)) ∈ R n. Specifically, for ΩN and given any mechanism (σ g, τ), if m′i is the announced type of agent i when his true type is mi and m−i is the true profile for agents N \ {i}, then the utility of i is given by vi(σ g(m′i , m−i), τi(m ′ i , m−i); mi ; s−i(m−i)) = −θi ( si + ∑ j∈Pi(σ g(m′i ,m−i)) s j ) + τi(m ′ i , m−i). Definition 10. A mechanism (σ g, τ) ex-post implements the general sequencing rule σ g if the transfer rule τ : Θn × S → Rn is such that for any i ∈ N, any mi , m ′ i and any true profile m−i, (18) vi(σ g(m), τi(m); mi ; s−i(m−i)) ≥ vi(σ g(m′i , m−i), τi(m ′ i , m−i); mi ; s−i(m−i)). Ex-post implementability requires truth-telling is a Nash equilibrium for any agent and for every true type profile m. Definition 11. A mechanism (σ g, τ) ex-post implements with balanced transfers the gen- eral sequencing rule σ g if the transfer rule τ : Θn × S → Rn satisfies ex-post imple- mentability condition (18) and is also budget balanced, that is for all m ∈ Θn × S → Rn, ∑ j∈N t j(m) = 0. Definition 12. A general sequencing rule σ̃ g is just if for each profile m ∈ Θn × S, the chosen order σ̃ g(m) satisfies the following property: for any i, j ∈ N such that θi ≥ θj, σ̃ g i (m) ≤ σ̃ g j (m).12 For any true m = (m1 = (θ1, s1), . . . , mn = (θn, sn)) we say θ is obtained from m if it is a collection of the first element from m j = (θj, s j) for each j ∈ N and we say s is obtained from m if it is a collection of the second element from m j = (θj, s j) for each j ∈ N. Similarly, for any i ∈ N and any true m−i = (m1 = (θ1, s1), . . . , mi−1 = 12The tie-breaking rule guarantees state contingent uniqueness of σ̃ g. 18 PARIKSHIT DE AND MANIPUSHPAK MITRA (θi−1, si−1), mi+1 = (θi+1, si+1), . . . , mn = (θn, sn)) we say θ−i is obtained from m−i if it is a collection of the first element from m j = (θj, s j) for each j ∈ N \ {i} and we say s−i is obtained from m−i if it is a collection of the second element from m j = (θj, s j) for each j ∈ N \ {i}. For ΩN , the just general sequencing rule satisfies the following: For any m = (m1, . . . , mn) ∈ Θ n × S, σ̃ g(m) = σ̃(θ) where θ is obtained from m. Definition 13. For σ̃ g, a mechanism (σ̃ g, τ̃) is a generalized rVCG mechanism if the trans- fer rule is such that for all m ∈ Θn × S and all i ∈ N, (19) τ̃ g i (θi , m−i) =    h g i (m−i) if P ′ i (σ̃(θi , θ−i)) = ∅, h g i (m−i) − ∑ j∈P′ i (σ̃(θi ,θ−i)) θjs j otherwise. where θ−i is obtained from m−i and h g i : Θ|N\{i}| × R |N\{i}| ++ → R is arbitrary. Proposition 3. The just general sequencing rule σ̃ g is ex-post implementable if and only if the mechanism (σ̃ g, τ) that implements it is a generalized rVCG mechanism. Proof: We only prove that if the just general sequencing rule σ̃ g is ex-post imple- mentable via a mechanism (σ̃ g, τ), then the mechanism is a generalized rVCG mecha- nism. The other part is easy and hence omitted. Consider any i ∈ N and fix any true type m−i for all agents other than i. For any true type mi = (θi , si) of i and any misreport m ′ i = (θ ′ i , s ′ i) by i, ex-post implementabil- ity of the just general sequencing rule σ̃ g requires vi(σ̃ g(m), τi(m); mi ; s−i(m−i)) ≥ vi(σ̃ g(m′i , m−i), τi(m ′ i , m−i); mi ; s−i(m−i)) which is the same as requiring (20) vi(σ̃(θi , θ−i), τi(mi , m−i); mi ; s−i(m−i)) ≥ vi(σ̃(θ ′ i , θ−i), τi(m ′ i , m−i); mi , s−i(m−i)). Moreover, given the true type m−i of all agents and given any pair of types (m ′ i = (θ′i , s ′ i), m ′′ i = (θ ′ i , s ′′ i )) for i with the property the waiting cost is identical in m ′ i and m ′′ i , σ̃ g(m′i , m−i) = σ̃(θ ′ i , θi) = σ̃ g(m′′i , m−i) since just sequencing rule ignores the process- ing time. Hence, using ex-post implementability, we get the following inequalities: (1) −θ′i(s ′ i + ∑ j∈Pi(σ̃(θ ′ i ,θ−i)) s j) + τi(m ′ i , m−i) ≥ −θ ′ i(s ′ i + ∑ j∈Pi(σ̃(θ ′ i ,θ−i)) s j) + τi(m ′′ i , m−i). (2) −θ′i(s ′′ i + ∑ j∈Pi(σ̃(θ ′ i ,θ−i)) s j) +τi(m ′ i , m−i) ≤ −θ ′ i(s ′′ i + ∑ j∈Pi(σ̃(θ ′ i ,θ−i)) s j) +τi(m ′′ i , m−i). Inequality (1) gives τi(m ′ i , m−i) ≥ τi(m ′′ i , m−i) and inequality (2) gives τi(m ′ i , m−i) ≤ τi(m ′′ i , m−i) and therefore, τi(m ′ i , m−i) = τi(m ′′ i , m−i). Hence we have (21) τi(m ′ i , m−i) = τi(m ′′ i , m−i) := τi(θ ′ i , m−i). INCENTIVES AND JUSTICE 19 Using (21) in (20) we get (22) vi(σ̃(θi , θ−i), τi(θi , m−i); mi ; s−i(m−i)) ≥ vi(σ̃(θ ′ i , θ−i), τi(θ ′ i , m−i); mi , s−i(m−i)). As long as the true type m−i of agents N \ {i} is known, the processing time of these agents s−i obtained from m−i is known and θ−i obtained from m−i is also known and hence the waiting cost cut-off vector (θµ(1), . . . , θµ(R)) for agent i with the just sequenc- ing rule σ̃ is also known and the calculation of the transfer for agent i is independent of the processing time of agent i. Therefore, from inequality (22) we get that for any given si > 0, the following inequality must be true. (23) Ui(σ̃(θi , θ−i), τi(θi , m−i); θi) ≥ Ui(σ̃(θ ′ i , θ−i), τi(θ ′ i , m−i); θi). Note that if inequality (23) holds for some given si > 0 and for all θi ∈ Θ, then for any other s′i > 0 with the same transfer, inequality (23) holds for any θi ∈ Θ since si (either actual or misreported) does not enter the calculation of the transfer τi(θi , m−i). The true processing time si only enters in the calculation of the completion time Si(σ̃). Inequality (23) is similar to the implementability inequality (1) with τi(θi , θ−i) of inequality (1) replaced by τi(θi , m−i) in (23) where θ−i is the waiting cost vector ob- tained from m−i. Moreover, the waiting cost cut-off vector (θµ(1), . . . , θµ(R)) for the just sequencing rule is same for both m−i and θ−i when θ−i is obtained from m−i. Hence for any true m−i, true θ−i obtained from m−i and any θi , θ ′ i ∈ Θ, we must have (B) τi(θi , θ−i) − τi(θ ′ i , θ−i) = τi(θi , m−i) − τi(θ ′ i , m−i). From (B) it follows that for any θi ∈ Θ, any true m−i and θ−i obtained from m−i, (C) τi(θi , m−i) −τi(θi , θ−i) := gi(m−i). Recall that implementability of the just sequencing rule σ̃ requires that the transfer must be an rVCG transfer, that is for any θ−i, and any θi ∈ Θ, the transfer τi(θi , θ−i) in (C) must be equal to the rVCG transfer τ̃i(θi , θ−i) given by (7). Hence from (C) we get (24) τi(θi , m−i) =    hi(θ−i) + gi(m−i) if P ′ i (σ̃(θi , θ−i)) = ∅, hi(θ−i) + gi(m−i) − ∑ j∈P′ i (σ̃(θi ,θ−i)) θjs j otherwise. where the functions hi : Θ |N\{i}| → R and gi : Θ |N\{i}| × R |N\{i}| ++ → R are arbi- trary. Without loss of generality, by setting hi(θ−i) + gi(m−i) = h g i (m−i) in (24) we get τi(θi , m−i) := τ̃ g i (θi , m−i) and the result follows. � That ex-post implementable with balanced transfers is not possible for ΩN={1,2} with two agents is a natural extension of the arguments in Proposition 2. By applying ar- guments similar to that in Theorem 3, it is easy to see that the just general sequencing rule σ̃ g is ex-post implementable with balanced transfers. 20 PARIKSHIT DE AND MANIPUSHPAK MITRA Definition 14. Consider the general sequencing problem ΩN with at least three agents. For σ̃ g, a mechanism (σ̃ g, τ̃ g∗) is a balanced generalized rVCG mechanism if the transfer rule is such that for all m ∈ Θn × S and all i ∈ N, (25) τ̃ g∗ i (θi , m−i) =              ∑ j∈N\{i} A j(θi)θjs j + g g i (m−i) if P ′ i = ∅, − ∑ j∈N\{i} B j(θi)θjs j + g g i (m−i) if Pi = ∅, ∑ j∈Pi(σ̃(θi ,θ−i)) A j(θi)θjs j − ∑ j∈P′ i (σ̃(θi ,θ−i)) B j(θi)θjs j + g g i (m−i) otherwise. where θ−i is obtained from m−i, A j(θi) := (σ̃j(θi , θ−i) − 1)/(n − 2), B j(θi) := (n − σ̃j(θi , θ−i))/(n − 2) and for any i ∈ N, g g i : Θ|N\{i}| × R |N\{i}| ++ → R is such that for any m ∈ Θn × S, ∑i∈N g g i (m−i) = 0. Proposition 4. Let ΩN be the general sequencing problem with at least three agents. The just general sequencing rule σ̃ g is ex-post implementable with balanced transfers if and only if the mechanism (σ̃ g, τ) that implements it is a balanced generalized rVCG mechanism. 5. CONCLUSIONS We have argued that the nice properties of the just sequencing rule from a mecha- nism design perspective are the following. (1) It is a Rawlsian sequencing rule which is implementable in dominant strategies. (2) It is an affine cost minimizer. (3) Its implementation is costless, that is, it is implementable with balanced trans- fers. (4) Unlike outcome efficiency, even when both waiting cost and processing time are private information it is ex-post implementable with balanced transfers. The cost of selecting the just sequencing rule is the efficiency loss, that is, the profile contingent difference in aggregate completion cost between the just sequencing rule and the outcome efficient sequencing rule. When the processing time of the agents are non-identical, this loss is positive for profiles where the order under the just sequencing rule is different from that of the outcome efficient sequencing rule. REFERENCES [1] Bergemann, D. and Morris, S. (2008). Ex-post implementation. Games and Economic Behavior 63, 527-566. INCENTIVES AND JUSTICE 21 [2] Bikhchandani, S. (2006). Ex-post implementation in environments with private goods. Theoretical Economics 1 , 369-393. [3] Chichilnisky, G. and Heal, G. M. (1997). The geometry of implementation: a necessary and sufficient condition for straightforward games. Social cHoice and Welfare 14, 259-294. [4] Chun, Y. (2006). No-envy in queueing problems. Economic Theory 29, 151-162. [5] Chun, Y., Mitra, M. and Mutuswami, S. (2014). Egalitarian equivalence and strategyproofness in the queueing problem. Economic Theory 56, 425-442. [6] Chun, Y., Mitra, M. and Mutuswami, S. (2015). A characterization of the symmetrically bal- anced VCG rule in the queueing problem. Article in press: Games and Economic Behavior, doi:10.1016/j.geb.2015.04.001. [7] Chung, K.-S. and Ely, J. C. (2003). Ex-post incentive compatible mechanism design. Working Paper, Department of Economics, Northwestern University. [8] Clarke, E. H., (1971). Multi-part pricing of public goods. Public Choice 11, 17-33. [9] Deb, R. and Mishra, D. (2014). Implementation with contingent contracts. Econometrica 82, 2371- 2393. [10] Dolan, R. J. (1978). Incentive mechanisms for priority queuing problems. The Bell Journal of Eco- nomics 9, 421-436. [11] Duives, J., Heydenreich, B., Mishra, D., Muller, R. and Uetz, M. (2012). On Optimal Mechanism Design for a Sequencing Problem. mimeo. [12] Groves, T. (1973). Incentives in teams. Econometrica 41, 617-631. [13] Hain, R. and Mitra, M. (2004). Simple sequencing problems with interdependent costs. Games and Economic Behavior 48, 271-291. [14] Hashimoto, K., and Saitoh, H. (2012). Strategy-proof and anonymous rule in queueing problems: a relationship between equity and efficiency. Social Choice and Welfare 38, 473-480. [15] Holmström, B., (1979). Groves’ schemes on restricted domains. Econometrica 47, 1137-1144. [16] Hurwicz, L., (1975). On the existence of allocative systems whose manipulative Nash equilibria are Pareto optimal. Mimeo, University of Minnesota. [17] Hurwicz, L. and Walker, M. (1990). On the generic non-optimality of dominant strategy allocation mechanisms: A general theorem that includes pure exchange economies. Econometrica 58, 683-704. [18] Jehiel, P., Meyer-ter-Vehn, M., Moldovanu, B. and Zame, W. R. (2006). The limits of ex-post imple- mentation. Econometrica 74, 585-610. [19] Jehiel, P. and Moldovanu, B. (2001). Efficient design with interdependent valuations. Econometrica, 69, 1237-1259. [20] Kayi, C. and Ramaekers, E. (2010). Characterizations of Pareto-efficient, fair, and strategy-proof allocation rules in queueing problems. Games and Economic Behavior 68, 220-232. [21] Fieseler, K. Kittsteiner, T. and Moldovanu, M. (2003). Partnerships, lemons and efficient trade. Jour- nal of Economic Theory 113, 223-234. [22] Lavi, R., Mu’alem, A. and Nisan, N. (2004). Towards a Characterization of Truthful Combinatorial Auctions. Working paper-School of Engineering and Computer Science, The Hebrew University of Jerusalem, Israel. [23] Maniquet, F. (2003). A characterization of the Shapley value in queueing problems. Journal of Eco- nomic Theory, 109(1), 90-103. 22 PARIKSHIT DE AND MANIPUSHPAK MITRA [24] Mitra, M., (2001). Mechanism design in queueing problems. Economic Theory 17, 277-305. [25] Mitra, M., (2002). Achieving the first best in sequencing problems. Review of Economic Design 7, 75-91. [26] Mitra, M. and Sen, A. (2010). Efficient allocation of heterogenous commodities with balanced trans- fers. Social Choice Welfare 35, 29-48. [27] Moulin, H., (2007). On Scheduling Fees to Prevent Merging, Splitting, and Transferring of Jobs. Mathematics of Operations Research 32, 266-283. [28] Mukherjee, C. (2013). Weak group strategy-proof and queue-efficient mechanisms for the queueing problem with multiple machines. International Journal of Game Theory, 42(1), 131-163. [29] Mitra, M., & Mutuswami, S. (2011). Group strategyproofness in queueing models. Games and Eco- nomic Behavior, 72(1), 242-254. [30] Rawls, J. (1972). A theory of Justice. Harvard University Press. [31] Roberts, K. (1979). The characterization of implementable choice rules. In Jean-Jacques Laffont, editor, Aggregation and Revelation of Preferences. Papers presented at the first European Summer Workshop of the Econometric Society, pages 321-349, North-Holland Publications. [32] Smith, W. (1956). Various optimizers for single stage production. Naval Research Logistics Quar- terly 3, 59-66. [33] Suijs, J. (1996). On incentive compatibility and budget balancedness in public decision making. Economic Design 2, 193-209. [34] Velez, R. A. (2011). Are incentives against economic justice? Journal of Economic Theory 146, 326- 345. [35] Vickrey, W. (1961). Counterspeculation, auctions and competitive sealed tenders. Journal of Finance 16, 8-37. [36] Walker, M. (1980). On the non-existence of dominant strategy mechanisms for making optimal public decisions. Econometrica 48, 1521-1540. [37] Zhou, L. (2007). The failure of Groves mechanisms in canonical allocation models. Mimeo, Arizona State University. ECONOMIC RESEARCH UNIT, INDIAN STATISTICAL INSTITUTE, KOLKATA, INDIA. E-mail address: parikshit r@isical.ac.in ECONOMICS RESEARCH UNIT-INDIAN STATISTICAL INSTITUTE, KOLKATA-700108, INDIA. E-mail address: mmitra@isical.ac.in work_icpel7dxn5ha3b6lry3m4d4s2a ---- Microsoft Word - LAW 2011_02.doc DEPARTMENT OF LAW EUI Working Papers LAW 2011/02 DEPARTMENT OF LAW SOCIAL JUSTICE AND ACCESS JUSTICE IN PRIVATE LAW Hans-W. Micklitz EUROPEAN UNIVERSITY INSTITUTE, FLORENCE DEPARTMENT OF LAW Social Justice and Access Justice in Private Law HANS-W. MICKLITZ EUI Working Paper LAW 2011/02 This text may be downloaded for personal research purposes only. Any additional reproduction for other purposes, whether in hard copy or electronically, requires the consent of the author(s), editor(s). If cited or quoted, reference should be made to the full name of the author(s), editor(s), the title, the working paper or other series, the year, and the publisher. ISSN 1725-6739 © 2011 Hans-W. Micklitz Printed in Italy European University Institute Badia Fiesolana I – 50014 San Domenico di Fiesole (FI) Italy www.eui.eu cadmus.eui.eu Author contact details Hans-W. Micklitz 1 Professor of Economic Law European University Institute Florence, Italy Email: Hans.Micklitz@eui.eu 1 I would like the thank R. Sefton-Green, H. Muir Watt, N. Reich, T. Roethe, C. Torp, G. Miller, K. Purnhagen for extremely helpful comments and B. Schüller not only for his support in my research, but also for interesting discussions over a couple of months. The responsibility for all errors and misconceptions, however, remains mine. Table of Contents 1. How the Argument Goes ................................................................................................................ 1 2. The Socio-Economic and Political Background of Social Justice (in Private Law) in France, Germany and England .................................................................................................................... 3 2.1. The English Model – A Liberal and Pragmatic Design Fit for Commercial Use ................... 4 2.1.1. English Pragmatism and Two Explanatory Hypotheses ............................................... 4 2.1.2. The Gradual Intrusion of Social Justice into Labour and Consumer Law .................... 7 2.2. The French Model – A Forward Looking Political Design of a (Just) Society....................... 8 2.2.1. The Political Conception – A Tentative Explanation.................................................... 9 2.2.2. Politicising Private Law as Social Law ......................................................................... 9 3.3. The German Model – An Authoritarian Paternalistic-Ideological though Market Orientated Design ................................................................................................................................... 11 3.3.1. Ideological Paternalism and Market Pragmatism........................................................ 11 3.3.2. Authoritarian Liberalism and the Rise of Labour Law and Consumer Law ............... 12 4. The European Integration Process and the European Model of Justice........................................ 13 4.1. The Evolving Character of the European Legal Order and the Rise of ‘The Social’............ 14 4.2. The Impact of the European Integration Process on Labour and Anti-Discrimination Law. 15 4.2.1. Labour Law and Anti-Discrimination Law ................................................................. 15 4.2.2. Consumer Law ............................................................................................................ 19 5. The European Model on Access Justice ....................................................................................... 21 5.1. Social Distribute, Access Justice and Allocative Libertarian Justice.................................... 21 5.2. The Two Constitute Elements: Access Rights and Anti-Discrimination Rights................... 23 5.2.1. Specific Access Rights in Labour, Anti-Discrimination and Consumer Law ............. 24 5.2.2. The Horizontal Dimension of Anti-Discrimination .................................................... 26 Bibliography.......................................................................................................................................... 28 Abstract During the C20th, the Member States of the European Union developed their own models of social justice in private law. Each model is inherently linked to national culture and tradition. However, all models have a common thread, which is the use of the law by the (social welfare) state as a means to protect the weaker party against the stronger party. Since the adoption of the Single European Act in 1986, the European Union has assumed a social outlook which has gradually developed over time eventually taking shape in the Lisbon Treaty and the Charter of Fundamental Rights. Since the adoption of the SEA, more particularly the White Paper on the Completion of the Internal Market,[1] the European Union adopted a huge set of secondary law means which influence either directly (consumer, labour, anti-discrimination and business law directives) or indirectly (directives meant to liberalise markets, e.g. telecommunication, postal services, energy – electricity and gas, transport, health care) private law matters. This new regulatory private law is governed by a different philosophy, one which cannot be brought into line with the understanding of social justice as enshrined in labour or later the consumer movement and one which is challenging national models of social justice in private law. I call the EU model of justice access justice/Zugangsgerechtigkeit (justice through access, not access to justice), i.e. that it is for the European Union to grant access justice to those who are excluded from the market or to those who face difficulties in making use of the market freedoms. European private law rules have to make sure that the weaker parties have and maintain access to the market – and to the European society insofar as this exists. Keywords Social justice, welfare state, private law, European integration, internal market, Zugangsgerechtigkeit, access justice [1] Completing the Internal Market. White Paper from the Commission to the European Council (Milan, 28-29 June 1985), COM (85) 310 final, 14.6.1985. 1 1. How the Argument Goes During the C20th, the Member States of the European Union developed their own models of social justice in private law. Each model is inherently linked to national culture and tradition. However, all models use the law by the (social welfare) state as a means to protect the weaker party against the stronger party, the employee against the employer, the tenant against the landlord and the consumer against the supplier. Therefore, social justice is bound to the idea of the redistribution of wealth from the richer to the poorer part of the society, individually and collectively. That is where the idea of the social welfare state is located. 2 The integration of social justice into private law and the rise of the welfare state were made possible by way of the grand transformation process that shook Europe between the 17th -19th century and that freed private law from feudal and corporative (ständische) barriers. 3 This transformation process is very much bound to the specificities of any given particular country, its economic and social conditions and also timing. Social justice itself is a product of the late 19th/early 20th century, a result of the socialist labour movement. Member States responded to this new challenge in various ways, mostly by transforming their private law systems through the ‘protective’ welfare state in the late 19th early 20th century. The second wave of social justice began after the Second World War with the rise of the consumer society. Again Member States’ private law systems were confronted with the call for social justice. This time the response came from the ‘regulatory’ welfare state. Social justice in private law cannot be understood in isolation from its origins, first in labour, then in consumer law. Labour law became a subject of its own and emigrated from the private law system into a separate area of law. Its ideological flavour along with its conceptual ideas did not abstain from touching the growing consumer law field. For a complete understanding of the different patterns of social justice in national private law therefore we must look at both labour and consumer law. The European Economic Community as construed in the 1950s was built on a clear separation of responsibilities between the EEC that was to establish the Common Market and the Member States that were to engage in social matters. However, the construction of the EEC changed considerably over time. Since the adoption of the Single European Act in 1986, the European Union has assumed a social outlook which has gradually developed over time eventually taking shape in the Lisbon Treaty and the Charter of Fundamental Rights. There is even an ongoing discussion on an existing or emerging European Social Model. 4 What matters in our context are the particularities under which social issues found its way in the European Union. Member States had developed their national labour laws long before the European Union turned into a political, economic and social actor. Therefore right from the beginning, European interest in gaining competence in social matters clashed with the settled interests in the Member States that tended to defend the already achieved status quo. The timid transfer of powers from the Member States to the European Union over the last 25 years is largely due to these tensions. Where the European Union 2 I do not want to claim that social justice can be equated with the social welfare state. In fact, it is necessary to distinguish between the protective welfare state of the late 19th century and the regulatory welfare state which emerged in the second half of the 20th century. I would like to thank C. Torp for this clarification. 3 See Wieacker, F. (1967), Privatrechtsgeschichte der Neuzeit, 2. Auflage, Göttingen. 4 See Rödl, F. (2009), ‘Europäische Arbeitsverfassung’ to be published in A. Bogdandy (ed.), Europäisches Verfassungsrecht, 2. Auflage, will also be published in English by the same editors in the course of the year; Scharpf, F. W. (1991), Crisis and Choice in European Social Democracy, Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press; Countouris, N. (2009), ‘European Social Law as an Autonomous Legal Discipline’, in P. Eeckhout and T. Tridimas (eds) (2009), Yearbook of European Law, 28, Oxford: Clarendon Press; Haar, B. and P. Copeland (2010), ‘What are the Future Prospects for the European Social Model?’, European Law Journal, 16 (3), 273-291. Hans-W. Micklitz 2 succeeded in gaining competence, not least due to globalisation pressure, the matters were either genuinely European in that they concerned transborder issues or the competence transfer was – often – instrumentalised by the Member States on the basis of ‘modernising’ 5 their national welfare systems which had become unaffordable. The situation in consumer law is different. Consumer law had not yet been settled in the Member States when the European Union assumed a leading role. 6 For this reason, consumer law is of particular interest for analysing the different concepts of justice, i.e. that followed by the Member States on one hand and Europe on the other, which clashed already in the process of making and shaping consumer law. However, the European Union at the beginning of the debate introduced a third vein of development. Art. 119 EEC Treaty on equal pay of men and women, already enshrined in the Treaty of Rome, set the tone for the development of a European anti-discrimination law, which reaches far beyond existing national concepts of equal treatment, thereby steadily intruding into ever wider realms of labour and nowadays private law. This third domain has no precedence in the Member States’ laws. Since the adoption of the SEA, more particularly the White Paper on the Completion of the Internal Market, 7 the European Union adopted a set of secondary law means which influence either directly (consumer, labour, anti-discrimination and business law directives) or indirectly (directives meant to liberalise markets, e.g. telecommunication, postal services, energy – electricity and gas, transport, health care) private law matters. This new regulatory private law is governed by a different philosophy, one which cannot be brought into line with the understanding of social justice as enshrined in labour or later the consumer movement and one which is challenging national models of social justice in private law. I call the EU model of justice access justice/Zugangsgerechtigkeit (justice through access, not access to justice), i.e. that it is for the European Union to grant access justice to those who are excluded from the market or to those who face difficulties in making use of the market freedoms. European private law rules have to make sure that the weaker parties have and maintain access to the market – and to the European society insofar as this exists. Access justice/Zugangsgerechtigkeit is not to be equated with social justice and the meaning it has developed over the 19th and 20th century in nation states. The European model of justice does not exclude a co-existence with differing national models of social justice. Where the European Union claims ultimate responsibility, technically speaking via exclusive competence as realised through the maximum harmonisation doctrine, where market integration prevails over social regulation, social justice re-emerges – as it has always been since Roman times in the ius aequum 8 – in traditional fields of labour and consumer law via ‘front stage’ regulation, in the new fields of anti-discrimination law and in the private law that governs the liberalisation policy of regulated markets (energy, telecommunication, postal services, transport) via ‘back stage’ regulation. The analysis is split into two parts – an investigation of the different models of social justice in a selected number of Member States in part II followed by an analysis of the emerging European model 5 Eichengreen, B. (2007), The European Economy since 1945: Co-ordinateed Capitalism and Beyond, Princeton: Princeton University Press, NJF, pp. 335-341; Weatherill, S. (2009), ‘Competence and Legitimacy’, in C. Barnard and O. Odusu, The Outer Limits of European Union Law, UK: Hart Publishing, p. 17, who stresses the potential of EU law to overcome nationalism and protectionism in Member States. 6 Micklitz, H.-W. (2009), ‘The Visible Hand of European Private Law’, in P. Eeckhout and T. Tridimas (eds) (2010), Yearbook of European Law, 29, 3-60. 7 Completing the Internal Market. White Paper from the Commission to the European Council (Milan, 28-29 June 1985), COM (85) 310 final, 14.6.1985. 8 In the same direction, see Calliess, G.-W. and M. Renner (2009), ‘Between Law and Social Norms: The Evolution of Global Governance’, Ratio Juris, 22 (2), 260-280. Social Justice and Access Justice in Private Law of access justice in part III. Part II serves a hermeneutic purpose in order to demonstrate the European way in dealing with matters of social justice. I start from the premise that the different models of social justice in France, Germany and England can only be understood by identifying the respective socio-economic and political background. These considerations serve as a bridge and a starting point for contrasting my findings with the ongoing development of what is ambitiously called the European Social model. I will reconstruct the evolving character of the European legal order which gave way to the rise of ‘The Social’. The unbalanced legal order – economics prevail over ‘The Social’ – shaped the integration logic, facilitated the transformation of the national social welfare state and also yielded access justice but also led to the reappearance of ‘social justice’ in new forms. The final part is devoted to shaping access justice/Zugangsgerechtigkeit and seeking a balance between the different national concepts of social justice and the European model on access justice/Zugangsgerechtigkeit. 2. The Socio-Economic and Political Background of Social Justice (in Private Law) in France, Germany and England An investigation into the socio-economic and political background of social justice in private law cannot be conducted without a look into the past. Following Berman, 9 the starting point of such an analysis should be the 11th/12th century, the conflict between the Catholic Church (the spiritual power) and the emperor (the temporal power) which culminated in the conflict between Pope Gregor VII and Emperor Henry IV over the independency of the church from temporal power. Berman argues that the separation of spiritual and temporal power did not only initiate early state building, first of the church and then the emperor, but also the scholastic school of law. 10 The crusades requested by Gregor VII led inter alia to a much stronger exchange between the western world and the Eastern world and paved the way for the reinvigoration of the old Greek and Roman philosophy. One might equally argue that the starting point of my undertaking should be the discovery of America and the growing conflicts between the Spanish and the English empire. This would lead us to the 15th/16th century. My approach however is more modest. In line with the emerging issue of social justice in the 19th century, I will limit my considerations to the last two centuries. My initial idea – perhaps this is due to the fact that I presented the first version of this paper at a conference which took place in Paris in January 2007 – was to investigate the interlink between constitution building and codification. Whilst such a starting point offers hopefully interesting perspectives in comparing France and Germany, it falls short in taking the United Kingdom into account. If anything, a parallel may be drawn between the French Revolution of the late 18th century and German state building of the 19th century on the one hand with the Civil war and the conflict between the English Crown and Oliver Cromwell in the 17th century on the other. This is roughly the period I proceed to investigate in attempting to explain where the different patterns of justice derive from. A look into the past shall contribute to a deeper understanding of social justice in private law. I must therefore equally explain how I understand and use history. History as a science has long been dominated by social, cultural and economic history. In my context, such an approach would mean analysing the interplay of constitution building and codification in the common law and the continental legal system. The mainstream approach in history, however, has changed. Today, research focuses on the reconstruction on consciousness and mentality. 11 More and more, this is done in a comparative perspective, comparative history is therefore gaining ground. 12 This is also true with 9 Berman, H,J. (1991), Recht und Revolution. Die Bildung der westlichen Rechtstradition, Frankfurt p. 144 et seq. 10 Berman, H.J. (1991), Recht und Revolution. Die Bildung der westlichen Rechtstradition, Frankfurt, p. 146 and p. 215. 11 See Raulff, U. (ed.) (1987), Mentalitätengeschichte. Zur historischen RekonstrUktion geistiger Prozesse, Berlin; Schulze, H. (1985), ‘Mentalitätsgeschichte – Chancen und Risiken eines Paradigmas der franzö- sischen Geschichtswissenschaft’, Geschichte in Wissenschaft und Unterricht, 36, 247-270. 12 Since 1993, there exists a particular review which is devoted to this task: European Review of History. Hans-W. Micklitz 4 regard to legal theory. D. Kennedy 13 uses such an approach in his path-breaking analysis of the ‘Two (Three) Globalizations of Law and Legal Thought’ in the last two centuries. In taking a general approach, we can assume that the French Constitution and the French Civil Code are 200 years old, the German Constitution is that of 1871 and the Civil Code approximately 100 to 150 years old and that the Declaration of Civil rights and the development of the common law preceded the two. 2.1. The English Model – A Liberal and Pragmatic Design Fit for Commercial Use On the surface, the challenge is that in English history there is no comparable event to the adoption of the Civil Code in France or in Germany. The civil war took place in the 17th century and led to major changes in society and in the parliamentarian system. But, it neither yielded a constitution nor a coherent codified body of civil law, rather, it made way for the Declaration of the Bill of Rights in 1689. The French and the German legal systems, seen through the eyes of a common law lawyer (daring to suggest that this is possible for me, a civil law lawyer) share a relatively homogenous view on the role and function of social justice in society. They are united in the idea of universal values that infiltrate legal principles and concepts. This is exactly where common lawyers run into difficulties. So the true difference between continental law and common law must be deeper and the reasons must date further back than the French revolution. We have to identify the break-even point from which the continental legal and the common law system diverged in following different paths. I will tie my considerations to the clash between different philosophies, to the remaining influence of the scholastic in continental Europe and to its growing critique through nominalism in the UK. This was also around the time when the relative cultural unity of Europe broke into pieces. 14 I think it is empiricism which is responsible for the deep differences between continental and common law legal systems. Empiricism paved the way for utilitarianism – and here we have the key to understanding the English reservations against the realisation of social justice through law. 2.1.1. English Pragmatism and Two Explanatory Hypotheses My view on the English legal system is stamped by empirical research that was undertaken some ten years ago on the management of emergency situations with regard to unsafe consumer goods. 15 We (the authors of the book) compared the handling of the emergency management of the very same accidents that occurred in France, Germany and the United Kingdom i.e. exploding office chairs in public buildings ( due to a breakage-prone gas cylinders) and the so-called glycol wine accident. We analysed the law in the books and the law in action. Our findings can be summed up in the following way: The French engineers and lawyers in the country asked themselves what Paris was doing, the German administrators were seeking the appropriate rules and the English administrators asked where the problem was. As far as Germany is concerned, we found our findings confirmed in a recent empirical study on product safety management in the Baltic Economic Area. 16 13 Kennedy, D. (2003), ‘Two Globalizations of Law & Legal Thought: 1850-1968’, Suffolk University Law Review, 36 (3), 631-679; Kennedy, D. (2006), ‘Three Globalizations of Law and Legal Thought: 1850-2000’, in D. Kennedy, The New Law and Economic Development, Cambridge University Press, p. 19. 14 Berman, H.J. (1991), Recht und Revolution. Die Bildung der westlichen Rechtstradition, Frankfurt, p.265. 15 Micklitz, H.-W. and T. Roethe and S. Weatherill (eds) (1994), Federalism and Responsibility - A study on Product Safety Law and Practice in the European Community, London: Graham & Trotmann. 16 Micklitz H.-W. and T. Roethe (2008), ‘ProdEnglandtsicherheit und Marktüberwachung im Ostseeraum – Rechtsrahmen und Vollzugspraxis’, VIEW Schriftenreihe, 26. Social Justice and Access Justice in Private Law It is English pragmatism that is characteristic for the handling of the legal system. Two issues arise whenever one attempts to define the differences between the civil law and the common law: first, the use of case law in preference to legal principles; and, second, the use of purposive interpretation. 17 Civil law lawyers reason downwards from abstract principles embodied in a code, whereas common law lawyers reason upwards from the facts, moving gradually from case to case. Civil law lawyers search for the Zweck im Recht, the purpose and objective behind the legal ruling if the wording of the rule to be applied, its position in the broader framework of the code in which the rule is embedded or the history of the rule do not provide guidance. Common law lawyers at least in the UK – maybe less so in the US – view purposive interpretation as an alien element. 18 Lord Goff sums up these differences as follows: 19 “Continental lawyers love to proclaim some great principle, and then knock it into shape afterwards. Instead, the boring English want to find out first whether and, if so, how these great ideas are going to work in practice. This is not at all popular with the propagators of the great ideas.” The careful reasoning of English judges is admirable, as is their focus on the wording of the rule in question, the elaboration of the meaning of the rule, and their careful explanation of the application of the rule to the particular facts of the case. 20 It is this peculiarly British pragmatism in looking at where the problem lies and at how to find an answer in the case law and/or in the rules which is so startling to a civil law lawyer who is fixated on rules. 21 The quotation from Lord Goff may find its deeper origin in three strands, (1) common law was and is first and foremost commercial law 22 as the English legal system was never easily accessible for the man in the streets. Ever since the costs to go to court were simply too high; (2) the practising lawyers, the QCs were selecting the judges. That is why judges benefitted from a strong commercial legal background and (3) judges play a much more dominant role in the common law system than in the civil law systems, both institutionally and individually. 23 However, the adversary system also limits what common law judges can do as compared to with judges in Germany and in France. We can transfer this attitude easily to the issue of social justice. There is deep reservation against the existence of universal principles that enters into the common (commercial) law system from the outside, from politics or deeper from particular socio-philosophical ideas. With regard to potential differences in Europe, pragmatism is an extremely helpful tool in 17 Lord R. Goff (1997), ‘The Future of the Common Law’, International and Comparative Law Quarterly, 46 (4), 745; Markesinis, B.S. (1994), ‘Learning from Europe and Learning in Europe’, in B. S. Markesinis (ed.), The Gradual Convergence: Foreign Ideas, Foreign Influences and English Law on the Eve of the 21st Century, p. 1; Koopmans, T. (1991), ‘The Birth of European Law at the Cross Roads of Legal Traditions’, The American Journal of Comparative Law, 39 (3), 493. 18 See, inter alia, Judge Bingham in Customs and Excise Commissioners v. ApS Samex (1983) 1 All ER 1042, at 1056. 19 Lord R. Goff (1997), ‘The Future of the Common Law’, International and Comparative Law Quarterly, 46 (4), 745; see also Goode, R. (2001), ‘Insularity or Leadership? The Role of the United Kingdom in the Harmonisation of Commercial Law’, International and Comparative Law Quarterly, 50 (4), 751, quoting Lord Wilberforce ‘The elegance, style and analytical powers of the British legal community have survived the decline of the British Empire intact.’ 20 Markesinis, B.S. (1994), ‘Learning from Europe and Learning in Europe’, in B. S. Markesinis (ed.), The Gradual Convergence: Foreign Ideas, Foreign Influences and English Law on the Eve of the 21st Century, p. 1. 21 Micklitz, H.-W. and T. Roethe and S. Weatherill (eds) (1994), Federalism and Responsibility - A study on Product Safety Law and Practice in the European Community, London: Graham & Trotmann. 22 Collins, H. (2009), ‘Lord Hoffmann and the Common Law of Contract’, European Review of Contract Law, 5 (4), 474-484, demonstrates the influence of one single judge, Lord Hoffman, to hammer down and to defend the traditional concept of contract law in today’s time. 23 Weber, M. [1922] 1980, Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft. Grundriß der verstehenden Soziologie, Tubingen: J.C.B. Mohr, p. 511; Collins, H. (2009), ‘Lord Hoffmann and the Common Law of Contract’, European Review of Contract Law, 5 (4), 474-484 and in particular the forceful critic of Bentham, J. [1798] (1907), An introduction to the principles of morals and legislation, Oxford: Clarendon Press, see under Part II, 1.1.3. Hans-W. Micklitz 6 managing differences. Therefore, a particular English view would be to simply accept that there are different concepts in Europe. This, however, does not mean that these differences have become part of the intellectual mindset (verinnerlicht). My hypothesis is that only by understanding English pragmatism can we comprehend English reservations against achieving social justice through law. In light of my argument that the differences between the continental legal system and the common law system can only be explained by the drifting apart of two major philosophical currents, rooted in the socio-economic environment of the respective centuries, I would like to point to two major events. This will not be possible without necessary simplifications: Firstly the clash between the scholastic and nominalism. The crusades linked the Western world to the Arabic world, helped to establish the Italian cities (Venice) as world trade centres, and – this is our point – brought Arabic discourse on ancient Greek philosophers (Aristotle and Platon) to Europe. The fall of Constantinople enhanced the influence of the Greek language and Greek philosophers in the Western World. These ideas called into question not only main stream scholastic thinking (here being understood in the meaning of Thomas von Acquin – in particular his concept of universalism) but also the world concept of the church, according to which trade should play a limited role. The critique against the scholastic found its expression in the growing importance of nominalism in the C14th and C15th, in particular in England. Nominalism paved the way for English reservations against ‘grandes idées’ and big legal principles. Secondly the rise of empiricism which is bound to the birth of the English trading state (Handelsstaat in the late C16th and early C17th). 24 In continental Europe the feudalistic society changed gradually into societies of cities and merchants. Trade (i.e. the economy) turned into a function and a task to be managed by the state – the mercantile system arose. Under Elisabeth I (1558-1603) England succeeded in breaking its dependency from the Hanseatic League with the help of the Merchant Adventurers who got royal support in establishing world wide operating trade companies. 25 Commercial law was needed to manage English trade internationally. The philosophical counterpart to the social and economic change may be seen in the development from nominalism (Ockham) to empiricism (Bacon) to utilitarianism (Hume, A. Smith, Bentham). Both historical strings tied together shall justify my assumption that the continental European understanding of social justice in the meaning of distributive justice does not really comply with philosophical, historical, economic and legal structures in England or – to put it the other way round – that England has paved the way for a legal system which is deeply rooted in nominalistic and utilitarian thinking. In this way, the English way of viewing the role and function of law is much more economic (ökonomischer) in its basic assumptions as opposed to German Idealism (Kant, Fichte, Hegel, Schelling) or French Rationalism (Descartes, Pascal, Voltaire, Rousseau). It is a ‘shorter way’ from ‘utility’ to economic efficiency and economic effectiveness than from duty, understanding reason, will or spirit (Pflicht, Vernunft, Wille, Verstand, Geist). It can be much more easily adapted to European ‘integration through law’, where judges and the judicial system are given a major role to play. 26 24 Schulin, E. (1969), Handelsstaat England. Das politische Interesse der Nation im Außenhandel vom 16. bis ins frühe 18. Jahrhundert, reprinted in The American Historical Review (1975), 80 (1), 107. 25 See James, L. (1994), The Rise and the Fall of the British Empire, London: Abacus. 26 No research has been undertaken as to whether there is a link between the adherence of the UK to the EU and the deepening of European integration via case-law. Whilst the building blocks van Gend en Loos as well as Costa Enel had been decided before the UK joined the EU, the ground breaking judgment Dassonville and Cassis de Dijon which paved the way for the development of the Internal Market were taken with participation of UK judges. Today’s pattern of integration might have changed. C. Joerges, even speaks of ‘integration without law’ referring to the dominance of politics and the influential role of ‘governance’. Social Justice and Access Justice in Private Law 2.1.2. The Gradual Intrusion of Social Justice into Labour and Consumer Law There was no big bang in the English society which led to the development of social justice motivated legal regimes. The transformation from a feudalistic and corporative society to an open democracy occurred step by step. The Civil War certainly constituted a break even point, but the transformation process was very much guided by conflicts between the nobles on the one hand and the merchants on the other who wanted to have their say in the political arena. The rise of the labour movement, in legal theoretical language the rise of the ‘Social’ 27 , in the UK is bound to its transformation from a trading state to an industrial state at the beginning of the 19th century, a few decades earlier than in continental Europe. The decline of feudalistic structures and the rise of individualistic, social and moral philosophy provided scope within which the labour movement could grow. Thilo Ramm 28 in his analysis of the new ordering of labour law in the C19th and C20th distinguishes two principles, self-help and state-help. Self-help was the basis of trade unions and strikes. This was close to the dominating liberal understanding of the free play of market forces. The system of self-help replaced the notion of individual laissez faire with collective laissez faire. Self-help and collective laissez faire was a noble circumscription for a period of fight and conflict which led to compromises at both ends, between the trade unions and the trade associations and between the different political forces in Parliament. If Parliament took action it did so in response to concrete problems via isolated statutes and ad hoc political decisions. This is the particular British way of dealing with matters of justice. The collective laissez faire system and together with unemployment insurance legislation set up a stable system that lasted until the 1960s. If any, the short period under the (old) Labour government in the 1960s could be seen as the unique time in which statutory policy was used as a means to strengthen social institutions and law as a means of distributive justice in labour law. Both elements, self-help through trade unions and regulatory welfare state-help did not survive Thatcherism. The story of consumer law is a relatively young one. The debate started in 1960 with the Molony Report, which was requested by the labour government. It identified numerous deficiencies and injustices that were affecting individuals which were the basis of subsequent changes in the law. However, it took until 1973 before consumer policy as a political issue was widely accepted across the political parties. 29 The UK met the usual prejudices in that it did not formulate a comprehensive consumer policy program, like France or Germany, but rather reacted in a pragmatic-problem bound political way. In the field of private law, three major reforms took place in about four years, the Amendment of the Supply of Goods Act 1973, the adoption of the Consumer Credit Act in 1974 and the Unfair Contract Terms Act in 1977. All interventions created mandatory contract law, fully in line with main stream thinking of using consumer law as a regulatory tool to limit contractual freedom. However, there are differences between the continental approach on the one hand and the English approach on the other. The Unfair Contract Terms Act in essence prohibits exclusion clauses and does not subject contracts between business and consumers to a general fairness test, just as Germany and some years later France, which would have given judges the power to individually assess fairness in consumer contracts. The UK approach on consumer credit is less determined by a protective outlook than by guaranteeing a workable and feasible capital market. It combines private law and public law means. In Germany, consumer credit is certainly one of the areas where not so much the legislator but 27 Kennedy, D. (2003), ‘Two Globalizations of Law & Legal Thought: 1850-1968’, Suffolk University Law Review, 36 (3), 631-679; Kennedy, D. (2006), ‘Three Globalizations of Law and Legal Thought: 1850-2000’, in D. Kennedy, The New Law and Economic Development, New York: Cambridge University Press, p. 19. 28 Ramm, Th. (1986), ‘Epilogue: The New Ordering of Labour Law’, in B. Hepple (ed.) (1986), The Making of Labour Law in Europe. A comparative Study of Nine Countries up to 1945, London: Mansell Publishing, p. 277. 29 See Whincup, M. (1980), Consumer Legislation in the United Kingdom and the Republic of Ireland, New York, p.6. Hans-W. Micklitz 8 rather the courts play a predominant role in the protection of the weaker party. The famous intervention of the German Constitutional Court into collateral guarantees between the bank and the debtor’s daughter raised much concern even outside Germany. 30 There is no counterpart in the case law of the House of Lords (now Supreme Court). Most recently the Supreme Court made clear that there is no need and no justification under English law – even if it is implemented EU law – to introduce a protective design into consumer contracts. 31 Neither the Thatcher government in the 1970s and 1980s nor the new Labour government of Blair in the 1990s or in the beginning of this century brought about substantial changes in consumer law, with one exception: 32 the liberalisation and privatisation of former state incumbents in the field of telecommunication, energy and transport. Former customers were turned into market citizens rather than take-care consumers who freed from self-responsibility. The return to the market as the dominating power, self-help instead of statutory regulation, has a long standing history in the UK. Liberalisation and privatisation of former state monopolies can easily be connected to utilitarian thinking. 33 In this way, the UK preceded and strongly influenced development in the EU. 34 2.2. The French Model – A Forward Looking Political Design of a (Just) Society France has a particular standing in the legal and theoretical discourse on the interrelationship between constitution building, private legal order making and matters of justice. It results from the French revolution the results of which are still today stamping our understanding of ‘a’ constitution and ‘a’ civil code. The key events in France took place in the space of two decades, contrary to England where no such clear cut events, at least not with regard to constitution building and private legal order making, can be fixed. The Revolution led to a break 35 with feudalistic structures and instituted a bourgeois society governed by individual freedom and equality of rights that became even more visible in the Code Civil and in the French Constitution. 36 I start from two premises: Firstly, the vision of the French revolution which was proclaimed in the Declaration of Human Rights, pinned down in a Constitution and later codified in the Civil Code has deeper social, cultural, economic and intellectual roots. I will argue that today’s conception of social justice in France can best be understood as a political forward looking concept. This goes back to French Rationalism and Descartes. Secondly, French society may be characterised by the tension between, on the one hand, intellectual projects guided by the ‘grandes idées’ (what is right is useful) – the French Constitution and the French Code – which strengthen the power of the executive to the detriment of the power of the judiciary, and on the other hand, the highly politicised bottom-up resistance against an excessively far 30 Marella, M.R. (2006), ‘The Old and the New Limits to Freedom of Contract in Europe’, European Review of Contract Law, 2 (2), 264, in particular under reference to Teubner, G. (1999-2000), Ein Fall von strUktureller Korruption? Die Familienbürgschaft in der Kollision unverträglicher Handlungslogiken, Kritische Vierteljahreszeitschrift für Gesetzgebung und Rechtswissenschaft, pp. 83 and 388. 31 Judgment, 25.11.2009, Office of Fair Trading (Respondents) v. Abbey National plc & Others (Appellants), Michaelmas Term (2009) UKSC 6 on appeal from (2009) EWCA Civ 116. 32 Howells, G. and Weatherill, S. (2005), Consumer Protection Law, England: Ashgate Aldershot, p. 78. 33 Howells, G. and Weatherill, S. (2005), Consumer Protection Law, England: Ashgate Aldershot, p. 78, underline the influence of v. Hayek in the way in which the England administered the privatisation process under the Thatcher regime. 34 Keßler, J. and H.-W. Micklitz (2008), ‘Kundenschutz auf den liberalisierten Märkten – Vergleich der Konzepte, Maßnahmen und Wirkungen in Europa – Personenverkehr/Eisenbahn,’ VIEW Schriftenreihe, Band 24; Keßler, J. and H.-W. Micklitz (2008), ‘Kundenschutz auf den liberalisierten Märkten – Vergleich der Konzepte, Maßnahmen und Wirkungen in Europa – Telekommunikation, VIEW Schriftenreihe, Band 25. 35 Arendt, H. (1963), On Revolution, London: Penguin Books. 36 Wieacker, F. (1967), Privatrechtsgeschichte der Neuzeit, 2. Auflage, Göttingen, p. 343. Social Justice and Access Justice in Private Law reaching executive power. The fight over ‘the Social’ demonstrates that social justice is a highly politicised matter throughout in society, subject to conflict, support or rejection. 2.2.1. The Political Conception – A Tentative Explanation Just like in England, the turning intellectual point can be attributed to the fading influence of scholastic thinking. It deliberated the spirit from methodological scholastic constraints and paved the way for a particular French rational method in philosophy. The founding father was certainly Montaigne (1533-1592). His epistemology went along with the Zeitgeist of the 16th century and the then radical scepticism ‘what do I know’. His major contributions led to the final discredit of the then existing knowledge as a result of a fully-fledged scepticism and an attempt to find a generally binding moral and social peace. Montaigne set long lasting incentives for critical reflection of all existing knowledge and values, what has been later named ‘Enlightenment’. Looking back, the 16th century may be regarded as a transitional period in which the old scholastic forms of thought were overcome, but where a new method to investigate the ‘truth’ and the concept of the truth was not yet developed. This was left to the 17th century. Descartes began with his Discours de la Méthode. He claimed that a particular method to acquire the truth is needed, which then allows to solve all philosophical questions. For Descartes ‘what is true is useful’ and not ‘what is useful is true’ like in utilitarianism. This is the key to understanding the particular French political conception. Descartes’ philosophy results in the priority of theory over practice which is the basic thesis of French intellectualism. The Cartesianism heavily influenced political life and the emergence of the absolute monarchy of Louis XIV. The fall of the absolute monarchy goes hand in hand with the rising criticism of Descartes’ philosophy – through Voltaire and Rousseau. What matters in our context is the critique of Locke and Hume against Descartes’ notion that man has natural ideas. Condillac and Helvetius instead argued based on psychological empiricism that men are equal from time of birth. This concept constituted the scientific basis for the French revolutionary ideas. The innovative and creative potential of French philosophy in the 17th century becomes clear when we look to the setting of new incentives in social philosophy and in the perception of the moral. They overcome the Cartesian metaphysic – revelation of natural laws through God, responsibility before God, reception of power of the sovereign from God – which might be largely due to moral decline. Moral standards should be defined by themselves. The different strains – Rousseau on the one hand and a more utilitarian vision inspired by English philosophers on the other – are united in the attempt to found a moral removed from theological and metaphysical requirements. This is the core of French laicity. 2.2.2. Politicising Private Law as Social Law Just like in England, the development of labour law is bound to the growing role of the labour movement, the establishment of trade unions and the rise of the protective welfare state. This does not mean that self-help and state-help took similar forms. The trade unions in France are much closer to the different political parties. Although somewhat exaggerated, one may assume that each party may be associated with a particular trade union and vice versa. That is why social conflicts between workers and employers bear a political dimension that cuts across different parties, on each side of the poles. The French state on the other hand is much more the protective welfare state in the German sense which understands or which has learned to understand under the constant and highly politicised pressure of the labour movement that it has to take workers’ interests systematically into account. Hans-W. Micklitz 10 From a French perspective the notion of labour law does not make much sense. It is much more correct to speak of ‘droit social’ which enshrines employment law and social security. Like in Germany ‘droit social’ developed outside the civil law system and roughly at the same time. 37 The governments of the ‘belle époque’ adopted three major laws, insurance against accidents at work in 1898, the ban on Sunday trading in 1906 and the social insurance system (pension and invalidity) in 1910. The French social laws and the French lawyers contributed substantially to the rise of ‘droit social’ in Europe and beyond, in particular after the First World War. The intellectual spirit of ‘The Social’ in the late C19th and early C20th is grounded in the path breaking philosophical work undertaken during the decline of the French absolute monarchy, with its focus on ‘moral’ philosophy. 38 Consumer law is a product of the consumer society, i.e. of the market society. Two particularities deserve to be mentioned. In the UK and in Germany consumer policy arose as a statutory policy, but in France the politicisation of consumer law is closely intertwined with the role and function of trade unions and other societal players in the public domain. When consumer policy reached the political agenda, the different trade unions entered the field and integrated the voice of consumers into their overall policy at least to some extent. The second particularity is demonstrated by the close links between labour and consumption may be demonstrated by returning to the roots of French consumer law and in demonstrating the resemblance between the two constitutive elements of labour and consumer law which point to the French Revolution. The system of statutory price control, which was forgone in the late seventies of the 20th century under pressure from the EU, had created strong and stable ties between the public and the private sphere, which found their expression in the way in which price fixing was used to introduce consumer protection issues. Opening up the market for consumer products, i.e. allowing the market to fix the price, meant that France had to set up a consumer policy which should accompany market liberalisation. Therefore, consumer policy in France has always been and still is highly politicised. It is exposed to strong political variations according to the political party which holds the power and is closely related to social trends, as promoted by trade unions. In Europe France took a leading role in the field of consumer information and consumer contract law. It fits well then that the French Government, more particularly the Minister of Economics, undertook a major effort in the early eighties to set a benchmark for the future of consumer law in Europe. The Commission de la Refonte, established by the Government and headed by Jean Calais-Auloy, intended to develop a coherent body of rules that would stand side-by-side with the Code Civil. 39 This ambitious project, which would have given France a leading role in consumer law, failed for various reasons, not least because of the growing importance of European consumer law. However, the project was originally designed as a forward looking project reaching beyond the elaboration of technical rules stressing a rather political message, the one of the role and function of consumers as citizens in a market society. The drafters even intended to transpose the model of declaring collective agreements generally applicable to standard contract conditions. 40 The decline of French consumer law as a forward looking design for the future is obvious. The EU project on a European Code on Civil Law endangers, from a French understanding, the unique role the 37 Haupt, H.-G. (1995), ‘Sozialpolitik und ihre gesellschaftlichen Grenzen in Frankreich vor 1914’, Jahrbuch für Wirtschaftsgeschichte, p. 171. 38 Kennedy, D. (2003), ‘Two Globalizations of Law & Legal Thought: 1850-1968’, Suffolk University Law Review, 36 (3), 649. 39 Proposition pour un nouveau droit de la consommation, rappport de la commission de la refonte du droit de la consommation au secrétaire d’État auprès du ministre de l’Économie, des Finances et du Budget chargé du Budget et de la Consommation, 1985. 40 Calais-Auloy, J. (1984), ‘Collectively Negotiated Agreements: Proposed Reforms in France’, Journal of Consumer Policy, 7 (2), 115-123. Social Justice and Access Justice in Private Law Code Civil enjoys in the civil law countries. This might explain the sometimes nationalistic reactions against the European project and the project ‘Catalan’ 41 which is meant to bring intellectual leadership back to France. Even the European Commission had to consider the ‘particular’ position of France and the French Civil Code in the European codification project. The ‘terminology group’, composed partly of the French academic Group constituted by the Société de Législation Comparée and the Association Henri Capitant des Amis de La Culture Juridique Française 42 , had to somewhat compensate for the German-Dutch-English-Polish dominated Study and Acquis Group. 3.3. The German Model – An Authoritarian Paternalistic-Ideological though Market Orientated Design The German Civil Code entered into force on the 1st January 1900. So the German Civil Code is a hundred years younger than the French Civil Code. In the aftermath of the Vienna Congress, the scattered German regions (kingdoms, counties (earldoms), regions) failed to unite in a German state, united by its own constitution. It took until 1871 before Germany managed, under the regime of the Prussian king/emperor and his chancellor Bismarck, to adopt a constitution. I will build my arguments around two major guiding assumptions: Firstly, there is a direct line from Kant to Savigny to the formal rationality of the private law system (Weber) which serves the execution of capitalist society. The Kantian philosophy inspired Savigny in the foundation of the so-called ‘Historische Schule,’ which gained dominating influence during the 19th century and which is still influential today. It has created a particular way of thinking which favoured the rejection of all social policy issues into the ‘pure’ private law system. Social issues were outsourced to special private law legislation outside the BGB. Secondly, there is the link between Hegel, Thibaut, German idealism, and legal naturalism, as expressed in Jhering, Ehrlich, Weber, Kantorowicz, where the national ideals were tied to social ideals of a society and a nation. Such a vision can hardly be connected to an authoritarian state that accepts the responsibility for guaranteeing protection in order to exclude political participation. The German version of legal naturalism favours an instrumental use of the legal system for matters of justice. 3.3.1. Ideological Paternalism and Market Pragmatism The late adoption of the constitution is mirrored in the equally late adoption of the German Civil Code. It is still worth studying the intellectual quarrel of the two German law professors, Thibaut and Savigny over the value of a codified German Civil Code, Thibaut fighting in Heidelberg enthusiastically – inspired by German Idealism and ‘les grandes idées’ of the French revolution – for a genuine German Code, Savigny fighting brilliantly (but not enthusiastically) for the maintenance of the old Roman law. 43 Savigny is the founding father of the German Historische Schule, which argues that law shall and cannot be derived from the ‘nature’ or ‘reason’ of the human being (Natur und Vernunft). Quite to the contrary law should and must be understood as a historical product of the spirit of the people 41 Cartwright, J. and S. Vogenauer and S. Whittaker (eds) (2009), Reforming the French Law of Obligations, England: Hart Publishing. 42 Fauvarque-Cosson, B. and D. Mazeaud (ed.) (2008), European Contract Law: Materials for a Common Frame of Reference: Terminology, Guiding Principles, Model Rules, Munich: Sellier European Law Publishers. 43 Thibaut, A.F.J. and F.C. v Savigny [1973] (2002), Ihre programmatischen Schriften, mit einer Einführung von Hans Hattenhauer, München. Hans-W. Micklitz 12 (Volksgeist). The task of the lawyer is not to constitute a meaningful legal order for human beings, but to collect and systemise the legal material produced by the spirit of the people. That is why it is called in a somewhat misleading way ‘Historische Schule’. History appears rather static. Law in this sense is kantesian formal (kantisch-formal), not inspired by ‘nature’ and ‘reason’ (Natur und Vernunft) as Hegel claimed. Savigny wanted to become the ‘Kant’ of the legal system (der Kant der Rechtswissenschaft). The ideals of Thibaut were reflected in Hegel’s philosophy who paved the way for studying history, its development and its dynamics of the development. 44 The raising legal naturalism (Jhering) contributed to a better understanding of the historical and present reality of legal orders. Most of the legal auxiliary sciences (rechtliche Hilfswissenschaften) such as criminology, Rechtstatsachenforschung (research on legal facts) as well as legal sociology (Rechtssoziologie – Eugen Ehrlich and Max Weber) have their origin in legal naturalism as well as the Freirechtsschule. 45 The dark side of legal naturalism, which is the standard formula, results from its strong believe in deducing from historical and present reality repercussions on the perfect model of justice which has to be achieved by a politically guided law that is supposed to achieve a particular social purpose. The tension between pragmatic market based legislation in the formal sense and the strong strive for social ideas is characteristic for the German political and legal system. Law making in the Germany of the early 19th century was understood as an academic exercise, quite contrary to the democratic discussion that surrounded the adoption and distribution of the French Civil Code. The Thibaut/Savigny conflict, the conflict between two leading professors, led to the instauration of the two law commissions again composed of professors which finally paved the way for the adoption of the German Civil Code, some fifty years later. The leading role of academics in Germany is certainly associated with the political – democratic – vacuum that resulted from the failed attempt in 1848 to establish a German nation. 3.3.2. Authoritarian Liberalism and the Rise of Labour Law and Consumer Law Social justice issues did not made their way into the German Civil Code. The political – statutory – response to distortions of the industrial revolution, the expropriation of the labour force and its disastrous effects to health and safety resulted in the establishment of a dense social security system, adopted in the last decade of the 19th century. Between 1881 and 1889, the German Reichtstag adopted the law on health insurance (1881), accident insurance (1883) and invalidity insurance (1889). In 1891 the introduction of the pension funds followed. These protective welfare activities had equally to compensate for the exclusion of the fourth class (the workers) from political power by the Sozialistengesetze. The explicit objective was to undermine the rise of the labour movement. The only way for workers to organise themselves was to unite in education circles, the so-called Arbeiterbildungsvereine. They constituted the nucleus for the organisation of the labour force after the collapse of the second German empire with the end of the First World War. The Republic of Weimar did not only bring a new democratic constitution, it also gave way to major legislative acts which enforced the labour movement, from 1922 on work councils (Betriebsräte) which granted workers rights to participate in the decision-making of companies. Already in 1915 Hugo Sinzheimer had forcefully advocated for the introduction of legislative means to declare collectively negotiated tariffs generally applicable. The project, however, was only realised in 1949. This time lag is characteristic for the delayed transposition of intellectual concepts into legal means. The Weimar Republic provided a fertile ground for ideas and concepts to give the economy a more democratic outlook (Napthatli). However, these ideas and concepts were only realised in the 1970s when Germany elected the first 44 Schwintowski, H-P. (1996), Recht und Gerechtigkeit. Eine Einführung in Grundfragen des Rechts,1, Berlin: Springer-Lehrbuch, p. 35. 45 Wieacker, F. (1967), Privatrechtsgeschichte der Neuzeit, 2. Auflage, Göttingen, p. 570. Social Justice and Access Justice in Private Law government in which the social democrats won the majority in the elections and adopted, in 1976, the law on codetermination (Mitbestimmungsgesetz). 46 The rise of consumer law brought the discussion between the two academic camps back to the fore (Professoren-Modell 47 ), a discussion which could only take place in Germany, as only German academics still hold a strong tradition in what constitutes in essence a political debate that becomes a legal debate. The question behind the question was whether the regulatory spirit of the old German Civil Code should be amended so as to integrate the missing social(ist) oil, not labour law but consumer law, into the German Civil Code – which had grown to a separate field of law outside the German Civil Code. The legal-political response to the consumer society which grew and grew in the aftermath of the Second World War remained timid and half-hearted. In an amazing historical continuity, consumer law grew outside the Civil Code in the form of special laws and regulations (Sonderregelungen = Sonderprivatrecht), commented and documented by the critical academia. Since 2002, consumer law provisions form part of the German Civil Code. This time, however, – some voices set aside 48 – there was no outcry in the academia, although the integration of the consumer contract law rules challenge the system and the coherence of the German Civil Code. In the shadow of the so-called modernisation of German contract law (Schuldrechts-Modernisierungsgesetz), the executive, i.e. the Ministry of Justice, smuggled the bulk of consumer contract law rules into the German Civil Code. The much more political dimension, the merging of technical, formalistic civil law (Savigny) and value loaded consumer law (v. Gierke), however, did neither attract public nor much academic awareness. The integration of consumer law into the German Civil Code has been performed as a technical bureaucratic exercise. Till today, academia largely ignores possible long term effects of the materialisation of private law through mandatory contract law rules and its Europeanisation through the integration of harmonised consumer contract law rules on the traditional body of consumer law. The old camps in civil law are still alive but their use of aggressive language and rhetoric has become subdued. 4. The European Integration Process and the European Model of Justice My hypothesis is that in the ECJ jargon, the ‘European legal order’ and the ‘European constitutional charter’ 49 has yielded, over the last fifty years, a genuine model of justice, which I term access justice (Zugangsgerechtigkeit) which differs from national concepts of social justice. This also means that the EU is not coalescing with the Member States’ models of justice. 50 46 Brüggemeier, G. (1977), Entwicklung des Rechts im organisierten Kapitalismus, Band 1: Von der Gründerzeit zur Weimarer Republik; (1979), Band 2: Vom Faschismus bis zur Gegenwart, Frankfurt: Sindicat. 47 Zimmermann, R. (2005), ‘Consumer Contract Law and General Contract Law: The German Experience’, Legal Current Problems, 58, 415-489; Schepel, H. (2007), ‘The European Brotherhood of Lawyers: The Reinvention of Legal Science in the Making of European Private Law’, Law and Social Inquiry, 32 (1), 183- 199; Kiesow, R.M. (2010), ‘Rechtswissenschaft – was ist das?’, JuristenZeitung, 586. 48 Adomeit, K. and H. Marcuse (2004), ‘der Verbraucherschutz und das BGB,’ Neue Juristische Wochenschrift, 579, 827-838; Adomeit, K. (1994), ‘Die gestörte Vertragsparität – ein Trugbild’, Neue Juristische Wochenschrift, 2467; Flume, W. (2000), ‘Vom Beruf unserer Zeit für die Gesetzgebung’, Zeitschrift für Wirtschaftsrecht, 1727. 49 Walker, N. (2006), ‘Big ‘C’ or Small ‘c’?’, European Law Journal, 12 (1), 12-14. 50 It might be particularly interesting to discuss whether and to what extent it was possible for the EU – and not for the Member States – to realise the principle of equal treatment in family law and later in private law per se, see Kennedy, D. (2003), ‘Two Globalizations of Law & Legal Thought: 1850-1968’, Suffolk University Law Review, 36 (3), 631-679, where he points out that the continental European countries as well as common law countries were unable to realise equal treatment in family matters during the peak time of ‘The Social’. Hans-W. Micklitz 14 4.1. The Evolving Character of the European Legal Order and the Rise of ‘The Social’ Since the late nineties there are two issues that have dominated the European legal discourse, 51 the development of a European Constitution and the making of a European Civil Code. If both the Constitution and the Civil Code were to be realised they would bring the European Union much nearer to the concept of a nation state as developed in the 17th century. At a first albeit superficial glance, the historical similarities between state building and code-making in France at the end of the 18th beginning of the 19th century and the current debate on Europe’s future are striking. These similarities have, however, neither been seen nor been subject to debate at either political or legal theoretical level. In fact, both grand projects are strongly interconnected via questions of their feasibility, of the degree to which they take into account ‘The Social’, via the shaky legitimacy of the founding fathers – the European Convention and the Acquis/Study Group, – via the unclear mandates/competencies of the drafters, via the particular character of a European Constitution and a European Civil Code in contrast to national constitutions and civil codes, via the ambitious though somewhat misleading use of the word ‘constitution’ and ‘Civil Code’ and in sum via ideological preconceptions. 52 In the meanwhile both projects, the grand constitutional project and the grand civil law project, ‘failed’. Maybe one reason can be found in the blatant neglect of the inner links between the two projects, in particular the link between a Social Model that could and should guide the debate over a European constitution and the development of a new European private legal order that bears a social outlook. Such an undertaking would have entailed the need to discuss, in the respective democratic fora, matters of justice at the European level. Both grand projects have been guided by a similar philosophy, i.e. that European integration is regarded very much like a technical process concerned with the development of correct rules that contribute to the furtherance of market integration rather than a controversy over social political aims and perspectives. 53 The technocratic nature of the debate served an important purpose by depoliticizing the discussion in domestic political circles. This does not mean that the grand projects do not deal with ‘justice’ or do not enshrine a particular model of justice, but such a model remains hidden either behind or amidst technicalities or ‘grand words’ without any specification or meaning. 54 The material substance of the European Constitution was ‘saved’ in the Lisbon Treaty. The European Civil Code project led to intensive academic debates and the production of the Acquis Principles 55 and the Draft Common Frame of Reference. 56 The latter comes near to a fully-fledged European Civil Code in its form as an ‘academic exercise’, 57 without, however, political support from the European 51 For an account of the theoretical strains in the debate, Walker, N. (2005), ‘Legal Theory and the European Union: A 25th Anniversary Essay’, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 25 (4), 581-601. 52 Micklitz, H.-W. and F. Cafaggi (eds) (2010), The European Private Law after the Common Frame of References, Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Publishing. 53 See for an early critique of the technical a-political character of the codification project of the European Commission in Social Justice Study Group (2004), ‘Social Justice in European Contract Law: A Manifesto’, European Law Journal, 10 (6), 653-674 and on the outcome of the project see Hesselink, M.W. (2008), ‘CFR & social justice: a short study for the European Parliament on the values underlying the draft common frame of reference for European private law: what roles for fairness and social justice?’, Centre for the Study of European Contract Law Working Paper Series No. 2008/04, who gives a relatively positive account of the degree to which social justice has been taken into account. 54 See Art. 2 of the Lisbon Treaty where ‘justice’ as one of the EU values is listed. 55 2007. 56 Outline edition, 2009. 57 I do not regard the production of the DCFR as a mere academic exercise as the drafters were actually working as legislators with a political mandate in mind. Social Justice and Access Justice in Private Law Council and the European Parliament. 58 Whether the DCFR will be ‘saved’ as a political project remains to be seen. However, the newly appointed European Commission has now taken a political initiative in order to translate the ‘academic Draft Common Frame of References’ into a political draft. The collaboration between the European Commission and the European Academia resembles, in an ominous way, the German Professorenmodell where the academia co-operate with an authoritarian executive, overstepping a weak parliament. 59 What remains out of the similarities between 19th century France and 21st century Europe, however, are insights on the differences between national and European constitution building and national and European civil law code making. The lesson to be learned is that the European legal order should be understood as a legal system and a polity under constant and ongoing construction. The evolutionary character is characteristic for the European legal order. ‘The Social’ has been gradually established over the last 50 years. Just like at the Member States’ level, ‘The Social’ means first of all labour law and social security. It is an open secret that this domain still remains rather underdeveloped. Consumer law, quite to the contrary, is a field in which the European Union has been setting incentives for the last 25 years. Anti-discrimination law might serve as a bridge between the two. It connects labour law and consumer law as it cuts across the various parts of the economy and the society. Anti- discrimination law is about to become the identity mark of the European Union. 60 This conglomerate of rules is going to yield a genuine European model of justice. Such a model of European justice, and I start from the premise that there is one, has to be dug out of the wedge of EU rules which are enshrined in these three areas and brought to the limelight not only of the academic debate. 4.2. The Impact of the European Integration Process on Labour and Anti-Discrimination Law 4.2.1. Labour Law and Anti-Discrimination Law The development of the substantive EU labour law may be broken down to three major trends. The Rome Treaty introduced, under pressure from France, Art. 119 (Art. 141, Art. 157 TFEU) on equal payment of men and women. A most active court and a responsive EU legislator backed by a number of Treaty amendments in particular via the Treaty of Amsterdam took an active stand. Art. 13 (Art. 19 TFEU) and Art. 141 (3) (Art. 157 TFEU) transformed the rules on the equal payment principle into a general principle of anti-discrimination via Treaty amendments and secondary Community law. Its role, function and reach in private law are subject to a controversial debate. 61 The second relatively stable and coherent field where the EU holds competence since the introduction of Art. 118 a) (Art. 137, Art. 153 TFEU) into the Single European Act, is health and safety at work. Here too, the EU has demonstrated considerable law-making activeness. The third area is rather broad and covers a whole range of legal issues, demonstrating that despite all the impressive activities of the EU, labour law remains rather pointillistic till today. The OMC may be regarded as a separate trend or branch of EU labour law. It has, however, not really changed the sketchy picture of EU labour law despite all the activities which have been taken under the new regime. 58 See in so far, Hesselink, M.W. (2008), ‘CFR & social justice: a short study for the European Parliament on the values underlying the draft common frame of reference for European private law: what roles for fairness and social justice?’, Centre for the Study of European Contract Law Working Paper Series No. 2008/04. 59 Schepel, H. (2007), ‘The European Brotherhood of Lawyers: The Reinvention of Legal Science in the Making of European Private Law’, Law and Social Inquiry, 32 (1), 183-199. 60 In this direction see, Münch, R. (2008), Die Konstruktion der europäischen Gesellschaft: zur Dialektik von transnationaler Integration und nationaler Desintegration, Frankfurt/Main: Campus-Verl. 61 Critical Säcker, F.J. (2006), ‘Vertragsfreiheit und Schutz vor Diskriminierung’, ZEuP, 1ff. and Basedow, J. (2008), ‘Grundsatz der Nichtdiskriminierung’, ZEuP, 230-251; supportive, Vandenberghe, A.-S. (2007), ‘The Economics of the Non-Discrimination Principle in General Contract Law’, European Review of Contract Law, 3 (4), 420. Hans-W. Micklitz 16 All three strains of development are united in one perspective, they demonstrate how much the EU is focussed on opening up markets for workers, on fighting against discrimination in access requirements, in short, granting access justice/Zugangsgerechtigkeit, thereby leaving the social welfare ‘after care’ to the responsible Member States. Three phases can be indentified: co-ordination of national laws and policies, European legislative activism and European hegemony, which allow for structuring the potential impact of the rise of ‘The Social’ at the EU level concerning matters of social justice. Co-ordination: Art. 119/Art. 141, today Art. 157 TFEU did not provide for legislative competences in its initial form. This article constituted the battlefield of litigation between workers and employers, an area which the ECJ infiltrated via the preliminary reference procedure. 62 On the basis of Art. 100 (Art. 94, today Art. 103 TFEU), the EEC as it then was, unanimously adopted six directives which can be grouped into three topics: (1) Directive 75/117 on equal pay and Directive 76/207 (today Directive 2002/73) on access to employment, both strongly connected to the principle of equal pay under Art. 119; (2) Directive 75/129 on collective redundancies (amended via Directives 92/56 and 98/59) and Directive 80/987 on insolvency protection (amended by Directive 2008/94) and (3) Directive 77/187 on transfer of rights and Directive 91/533 63 on information of worker rights. The two Directives 75/117 and 76/207 deserve particular attention here since the ECJ developed ground rules for the judicial protection of individually enforceable rights 64 that were transferred from the field of equal pay and access to employment into all other fields of European law where the enforceability of subjective rights were at stake. 65 Without enforceable individual rights, access justice would have remained law in the books. Legislative activism: Despite limited competences, the European Commission pushed for the adoption of a series of Directives, thereby taking control of at least one of the central issues of labour policy via minimum standards: the framework Directive 89/391 health and safety of workers, Directive 92/85 on the protection of pregnant women at work, Directive 93/104 on working time (amended by Directive 2003/88) and Directive 94/33 on the protection of young people at work. The addressee of the EU legislation is the particularly vulnerable worker, those exposed to dangerous working conditions, pregnant women and young people. Again, an abundant series of ECJ judgments could be reported where an active court stretched the boundaries of the scope of application of harmonised EU rules and strengthened individual rights to fighting for access. Maastricht brought the EMU but also new competences in the field of social policy with binding effects only for the remaining 11 Member States. This constitutional deficit was remedied in Amsterdam and paved the way for the UK to take over the set of four Directives adopted between 1994 and 1997. Art. 2 (2) of the Protocol led to the adoption of Directive 94/45 on the working council (as amended by Directive 2009/38) and Directive 97/80 on burden of proof (the latter was repealed by Directive 2006/54). Art. 4 (2) of the Protocol allowed for the introduction of Directive 96/34 on parental leave and 97/81 on part-time workers. The latter two are meant to strike down particular modes of discrimination. In Laval the ECJ interpreted the posting workers Directive 96/71as de facto and de jure laying down fully harmonised standards for the benefits of workers from the new Member States, thereby breaking down the barriers to the labour markets in the old Member States. 66 62 Micklitz, H.-W. (2005), The Politics of Judicial Co-operation in the EU – the Case of Sunday trading, Equal Treatment and Good Faith, New York: Cambridge University Press, p. 166. 63 Directive 91/533, though adopted after Directive 90/987 is still based on Art. 100 and what is even more important, it is guided by the same spirit as the previous five directives adopted between 1975 and 1980. 64 Micklitz, H.-W. (2005), The Politics of Judicial Co-operation in the EU – the Case of Sunday trading, Equal Treatment and Good Faith, New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 202 and seq. 65 See N. Reich, Bürgerrechte, 1999, §§ 8, 9, 14 at 228. 66 Judgment, 18.12.2007, Case 341-05, Laval un Partneri ECR 2007, I-11767 at 51-111; there is an interesting and controversial debate on how to read Directive 96/71, in particular on whether the minimax debate fits to the directive at all, see Deakin, S. (2008), ‘Regulatory Competition after Laval’, Cambridge Yearbook of Social Justice and Access Justice in Private Law The EU managed to introduce a new spirit into the new set of Directives, which can noted in two Directives, 94/45 on working council and 96/17 on the posting of workers. Both contain a strong cross border element and both rely on the image (leitbild) of a worker which resembles the circumspect and responsible consumer. The new ideal type of the European worker has to enforce her rights herself. Protecting pregnant women, securing the rights of the youth and granting parental leave, all these regulatory means are given an ever stronger economic element based on the premise that the EU labour market should remain open for everybody, not only for the male full time worker. An endless chain of ECJ judgments shaped the European labour law acquis (the established set of EU rules and ECJ case law) and contributed to the development of a new leitbild of the worker which is perhaps most prominently designed in the Bosman 67 judgment. Striving for hegemony: The third phase maybe characterised by three modes of regulation, a hidden mode, a new mode and an old mode in a new disguise. The hidden mode refers to cold harmonisation which results from the introduction of a single currency. Whilst the EU holds power, if any, to adopt minimum standards in all fields of labour law and policy where it has received competences, the practical effects of the EMU which became clear only after 1 January 2002 leads to a situation where Member States are deprived from using the national currency as a means to fight against unemployment. The welfare state is modernised by the back door – and through the EU. The new mode results from the introduction of the OMC in 2000 and its growing importance even outside core fields of labour policy such as social inclusion (OMC SPIC) and the European Employment Strategy (EES). 68 The OMC proceduralises social policy making and social policy enforcement by new modes of governance. Proceduralisation within new governance does not allow for setting clear cut standards on material justice. In this way, the OMC is much nearer to the model of ‘access justice’. There is, however, one area of labour law and policy, where the European Union has and is setting the tone more or less since the insertion of Art. 119 into the Treaty of Rome and independent from the ups and downs of the European integration process via numerous directives in the field of occupation and employment and via a proactive ECJ – the fight against old and new forms of discrimination not only between men and women. The Treaty of Amsterdam extended Community powers in Art. 141 (3) (now Art. 157 TFEU) and introduced Art. 13 (now Art. 19 TFEU), thereby paving the way for a series of Directives which, overarching the boundaries of EU labour law and policy, set down minimum standards in the fight against discrimination. Art. 141 (3) (Art. 157 TFEU) was used by the EU to amend Directive 76/207 by Directive 2002/73 and to recast Directive 76/207 via Directive 2006/54. In so far the EU changed competence, from Art. 100 (Art. 94) to the more specific rule in Art. 141 (3) (Art. 157 TFEU). Art. 13 (now Art. 19 TFEU) initiated three Directives, 2002/43 on equal treatment between persons irrespective of race and ethnic origin, 2000/78 establishing a general framework for equal treatment in employment and occupation and last but not least Directive 2004/113 for equal treatment between men and women on the access to the supply of goods and services. 69 The current situation: The anti-discrimination principle has found its way into the draft of the European Constitution. It is anchored in Art. 2 of the Union Treaty and Art. 21 of the Charter of (Contd.) European Legal Studies, 10 (10), 581-610 and Dougan, M. (2009), ‘Minimum Harmonisation after Tobacco Advertising and Laval Un Partneri’, in M. Bulterman and L. Hancher and A. McDonnell and H. Sevenster (eds.), Views of European Law from the Mountain: Liber Amicorum Piet Jan Slot, Kluwer Law International, p. 12-13. 67 Judgment of 15.12.1995, C-415/93, Union royale belge des sociétés de football association and others/ Bosman and others ECR 1995 I-4921. 68 Website of the European Commission, Social Affairs and Equal Opportunities, available at: http://ec.europa.eu/employment_social/spsi/joint_reports_en.htm (accessed at 14 November 2010). 69 See for a summary of the EC law on anti-discrimination, Rust, U. and J. Falke (eds) (2007), AGG Allgemeines Gleichbehandlungsgesetz mit weiterführenden Vorschriften; Kommentar, Berlin: Schmidt, p.198. Hans-W. Micklitz 18 Fundamental Rights 70 . It plays a prominent, though highly contested role 71 , in the ACQP and the DCFR. 72 The Mangold judgment 73 has raised a highly controversial debate on whether EU law knows a self-standing binding general principle of anti-discrimination, and whether such a principle is not only applicable vertically in citizen state relations, but also horizontally in citizen-to-citizen relationships. In its broadest reading, the Mangold doctrine lies at the heart of the (a) European principle of access justice/Zugangsgerechtigkeit as it would allow to guarantee access of EU workers to the labour market, access of EU consumers to the consumer market and access of EU citizens to all sorts of services, so long as they come under the scope of the EU law. Kücükdevici seems to grant horizontal direct effect to the Charter of Fundamental Rights. 74 If such a principle is enshrined in EU law, Mangold and Kücükdevici could serve as a tool for overriding the reservations of the UK, Poland and the Czech Republic against the integration of the Charter of Fundamental Rights into Union law. A new, though related battlefield has come up in Test Achats. 75 The more general question concerns what extent secondary community law can be submitted to a compliance test with the Charter of Fundamental Rights governed by access justice/Zugangsgerechtigkeit as the overall horizontal yardstick. In Bosman, 76 Angonese, 77 Viking, 78 Laval, and Olympique Marseille 79 the ECJ recognised the direct applicability of Art. 39 (Art. 45 TFEU) concerning the freedom of movement for workers, freedom of establishment in Viking Art. 43 (Art. 49 TFEU) and freedom of services in Laval, Art. 49 (Art. 56 TFEU). The ECJ has transgressed the boundaries between the public/private law divide and even turned vertical direct effect into a limited horizontal direct effect. 80 The worker is confronted with collective agreements that bear a quasi statutory character and that restrict her legal position. The right of free movement of workers is used so as to strike down collective private agreements that are either established by private organisations bearing a quasi statutory character (Bosman, Olympique Marseille) or by the states themselves (Angonese). Viking and Laval fit into that picture although the perspective is different. The parties fight for access against discriminating collective private agreements and the ECJ is granting access against the fierce opposition of trade associations and trade unions. 70 For a deeper analysis see Rust, U. and J. Falke (eds) (2007), AGG Allgemeines Gleichbehandlungsgesetz mit weiterführenden Vorschriften; Kommentar, Berlin: Schmidt, pp. 291 et seq and Basedow, J. (2008), ‘Grundsatz der Nichtdiskriminierung’, ZEuP, 230-248. 71 Säcker, F.J. (2006), ‘Vertragsfreiheit und Schutz vor Diskriminierung’, ZeuP, 1 and Basedow, J. (2008), ‘Grundsatz der Nichtdiskriminierung’, ZEuP, 230-248. 72 Art. 3:101 till 3:103 ACQP; II.-2:101 DCFR. 73 ECJ C-144/04 ECR 2005 I-9981; ECJ C-411/05 Palacios de la Villa, ECR 2007 I-8531. 74 (21) In that context, the Court has acknowledged the existence of a principle of non-discrimination on the grounds of age which must be regarded as a general principle of European Union law (see, to that effect, Mangold, paragraph 75). Directive 2000/78 gives specific expression to that principle (see, by analogy, Case 43/75 Defrenne [1976] ECR 455, paragraph 54). (22) It should also (emphasis added H.-W. M.) be noted that Article 6(1) TEU provides that the Charter of Fundamental Rights of the European Union is to have the same legal value as the Treaties. Under Article 21(1) of the Charter, ‘[a]ny discrimination based on … age … shall be prohibited’ 75 Opinion of AG Kokott - Case C-236/09 avaiable at http://www.lex.unict.it/eurolabor/en/documentation/altridoc/conclusion/c236-09.pdf. (accessed 14 November 2010). 76 ECJ Case C-415/93, ECR I-4921. 77 ECJ Case C-281/98, ECR I-4139. 78 ECJ Case C-438/05, ECR I-10779. 79 Case C-325/08, OJ C 247, 27.9.2008. 80 Reich, N. (2010), ‘Rights without Duties’ to be published in the Yearbook of European Law, (forthcoming 2011), p. 60. Social Justice and Access Justice in Private Law 4.2.2. Consumer Law The development of consumer law was initiated outside the scope of the clear competence rules under the Rome Treaty in the early 1980s. The adoption of the Single European Act led to the new Article 100 a), today Art. 104 TFEU, which granted the EU the power to take legislative action to complete the Internal Market taking a ‘high level of consumer protection’ as the basis. To understand the link between the White Paper on the Completion of the Internal Market, the Single European Act and the rise of consumer law it is still worth reading the most influential Sutherland report. 81 That is the source from where the well-known rhetoric of ‘an integrated market needs confident consumers’ derives from. 82 The Maastricht Treaty brought a genuine competence which was complemented in the Treaty of Amsterdam and enshrined in the Lisbon Treaty. Art. 169 TFEU has, however, never gained importance. All relevant measures were based on Art. 104 TFEU. In hindsight, the Europeanisation of consumer legal policy occurred in three phases. The first is still dominated by the varying patterns of national social justice, the second points already to the development of a deviating European model of justice, which is then subject to further specification and hardening in the third phase. Co-ordination: The first phase was determined by a policy of coordination of different national models of justice which purported to root the social connotation into European private law. 83 This is characteristic for all initiatives taken between 1975 and 1985, i.e. before the rise of the Internal Market. From the three directives adopted during this time span, two, Directive 85/577/EEC on contracts concluded away from business premises and Directive 87/102/EEC, bore a strong national protective bias. It is the weak consumer who is the addressee of regulatory action. Depending on the various patterns, the regulatory action is more or less linked to considerations of social justice. Legislative activism: After 1986, the White paper on the Completion of the Internal Market and the adoption of the Single European Act, the European Commission was in a much stronger position. It needed ‘only’ the support of the majority of the Member States and it benefited from the new competence rule. 84 Within a couple of years the EU managed to get quite a number of directives through the legislative machinery, some that had been pending for years, for example, Directive 90/314/EEC on package tours, Directive 93/13 on unfair terms in consumer contracts, Directive 94/47/EC on time sharing, 97/7/EC on distance selling, Directive 98/27 on injunctions and Directive 99/44/EC on the sale of consumer goods. The link between the completion of the Internal Market and consumer protection, however, gradually changed the outlook of consumer law, its contents, its direction and its concept. The protective device of consumer policy lost priority to the benefit or the detriment – depending on the viewpoint – of the now emerging image of the responsible consumer who was to play a central role within the European integration process. 85 That is where the genuine model of justice in EU has its roots. EU consumer law is market behaviour law. 86 European consumer 81 The Internal Market After 1992 Meeting the Challenge, European Parliament Doc (SEC 92-final) 2277 (1992). 82 See on the confident consumer Weatherill, S. (1996), ‘The Evolution of European Consumer Law and Policy: From well Informed Consumer to Confident Consumer’, in H.-W. Micklitz (ed.), Rechtseinheit oder Rechtsvielfalt in Europa?, Baden-Baden: Nomos, p. 423. 83 Critical as regards the objectives of consumer law, Calliess, G.-P. (2003), ‘Nach der Schuldrechtsreform: Perspektiven des deutschen, europäischen und internationalen Verbrauchervertragsrechts’, 203, Archiv für die civilistische Praxis (AcP), p. 575. 84 Micklitz, H.-W. and S. Weatherill (1993), ‘Consumer Policy in the European Union: Before and after Maastricht’, Journal of Consumer Policy Special Issue, 16 (3-4), 285-321. 85 Critical as regards the alleged change of the paradigm, see Rösler, H. (2004), Europäisches Konsumentenvertragsrecht: Grundkonzeption, Prinzipien und Fortentwicklung, Thesis Marburg, p. 74. 86 Reich, N. (2006), ‘Protection of Consumers’ Economic Interests by EC Contract Law – Some Follow-up Remarks’, Sydney Law Review, 28 (1), 37-62, quite critical on such attempts, Wilhelmsson, T. (2008), ‘The Contract Law Acquis: Towards More Coherence Through Generalisation?’, Europäischer Juristentag, 4 (1), 111-145. Hans-W. Micklitz 20 law is more and more turning into a consumer law without – or to put it in more cautious terms – with a less determined social protective outlook. The European ideal is the European consumer who shops across border in a relaxed though attentive and self-responsible manner. 87 Striving for hegemony: The third phase is linked to the policy shift initiated by the Lisbon Council that was hammered out in the 2002 consumer strategy. Maximum harmonisation ranks high on the European Commission’s political agenda. So far, it seems as if the European Commission has succeeded in transforming minimum standards into maximum rules in particular economic sectors. However, it has not managed to establish full harmonisation in legal fields which cut across various markets and sectors of the economy. Directive 2002/65/EC on distant selling of financial services constituted the break through in the realisation of the new paradigm. In a methodically interesting approach, of combining elements of Directive 2001/95/EC on general product safety, Directive 2005/29/EC on unfair commercial practices, it purports to harmonise unfair commercial practices with respect to B2C relationships. 88 Last but not least, the adoption of Directive 2008/48/EC on consumer credit followed suit, after a hard and protracted fight on the full harmonisation appraoch. 89 Directive 2008/122/EC replaces Directive 94/47/EC on time sharing with an even more detailed set of fully harmonised rules. A revised proposal to fully harmonise package tours is underway. The European Commission presented a similar approach in its 2008 proposal on a Directive on Consumer Rights which is meant to substitute Directives 85/577/EEC on doorstep selling, 97/7/EC on distance selling, 93/13/EEC on unfair terms and 99/44/EC on consumer sales. 90 However, it seems as if the European Commission has run into a deadlock situation. What does full harmonisation mean with regard to the separation of powers between the Member States and the EU in consumer law? 91 In what way does full harmonisation affect the dividing line between national protective concepts of justice and the EU model which puts emphasis on market behaviour and on a consumer who is circumspect and responsible? Full harmonisation takes away powers from the Member States. The hidden consensus between the European Commission and the Member States, which boosted the adoption of minimum protection standards in the aftermath of the Internal Market programme, has collapsed, not silently, but publicly (though widely unnoticed) in the Consumer Strategy 2002. The overall target formulated in the Lisbon Council to make the EU the most competitive market world-wide might bring about a major change in consumer policy and law, one which documents the end of the philosophy behind the Internal Market and the idea of the circumspect and responsible consumer. 92 The new consumer leitbild is the economically efficient consumer which has to operate no longer merely in European but in an international environment. 87 Heiderhoff, B. (2004), ‘Grundstrukturen des nationalen und europäischen Verbrauchervertrags-rechts, insbesondere zur Reichweite europäischer Auslegung’, Habilitation- München, pp. 289, 423. 88 Howells, G. and H.-W. Micklitz and T. Wilhelmsson (2006), European Fair Trading Law – The Unfair Commercial Practices Directive, Aldershot: Ashgate. 89 See Micklitz, H.-W. and P. Rott and L. Tichy (2007), Impact assessment of the revised proposal on consumer credit on the Member States legislation in Czech Republic, Germany and the United Kingdom, MS January 2007. 90 Commission of the European Communities. Proposals for Directive of the European Parliament and of the Council on Consumer Rights, COM (2008) 614 final; Micklitz, H.-W. and N. Reich (2009), “Crónica de una muerte anunciada: The Commission Proposal for a ‘Directive on Consumer Rights’ ”, Common Market Law Review, 46 (2), 471-519. 91 Weatherill, S. (2005), ‘Minimum Harmonisation as Oxymoron? The Case of Consumer Law,’ in H.-W. Micklitz (ed.), Verbraucherrecht in Deutschland – Stand und Perspektiven, VIEW Schriftenreihe, Band 20, p. 15 and Wilhelmsson, T. (2005), ‘European Consumer Law: Theses on the Task of the Member States’, in H.- W. Micklitz (ed.), Verbraucherrecht in Deutschland – Stand und Perspektiven, VIEW Schriftenreihe, Band 20, p. 37. 92 Micklitz, H.-W. (2009), ‘Jack is out-of the Box - The efficient Consumer-Shopper’, in T. Wihelmsson and. J. Bärlund, Festschrift, JFT 3–4, 417–436. Social Justice and Access Justice in Private Law The current situation: I started from the premise that ‘access justice/Zugangsgerechtigkeit’ might become the new paradigm of EU private law. Full harmonisation, however, brings a new dimension into EU consumer policy in that the question arises of who should deal with the protection of those consumers who do not met the efficiency doctrine. The Member States are barred from taking action in fully harmonised fields of EU private law. In a legalistic perspective, they are free to take action only in partially harmonised areas. It might then be for the EU to develop a social model in private law matters outside the dominating patterns of the efficient consumer/worker who may expect no more than ‘rough justice’, but a consumer/worker who even claims ‘social justice’. Can the EU rules on services of general economic interest serve as a fall back position? 93 Or will the Member States have to take the responsibility back for the protection of the weaker parties? Much will depend on the future of the full-harmonisation principle. 5. The European Model on Access Justice The EU model cannot be reduced to a formal libertarian concept of justice where the state is denied the right to forcibly redistribute wealth from one individual or group to another. I have shown in my analysis of the economic, social and political determinants that European labour, anti-discrimination and consumer law escape the polarisation between social distributive justice and allocative (libertarian) justice. What I want to show now is what this new pattern of European justice looks like. I will first try to locate the European concept of justice. It lies somewhere between social distributive and libertarian allocative justice. I will then look into the constitutive elements of access justice/Zugangsgerechtigkeit ‘access rights’ and ‘anti-discrimination’. I will limit myself to laying down the ground for discussion. The concrete legal implications of such a principle remain to be elaborated. 5.1. Social Distribute, Access Justice and Allocative Libertarian Justice Firstly, access justice differs from national protective concepts in that it does not aim at social protection in a redistributive perspective. The addressees of the EU labour, anti-discrimination and consumer law are not so much or not primarily the ‘poor who pay more’ – or, to allude to the famous study of Caplovitz 94 , the black or women who have to pay more for a new car than white men 95 – but rather the dynamic, open-minded, flexible, well-informed, self-standing and self conscious mobile worker or consumer who is seeking the best job opportunities and the best prices on the market of consumer goods and services so as ‘to reap up the benefits of the internal market’. 96 The normative leitbild, which is dominating EU labour and consumer law making, requires this omnipotent market citizen needed for the completion of the Internal Market and for making the EU ‘the most competitive and most dynamic knowledge-based economy’ in the world. EU labour, anti-discrimination and consumer law contain normative concepts such as the vulnerable consumer in Directive 2005/29 on unfair commercial practices or in the field of services of general economic interests which seem to run counter to such a Leitbild and to indicate a more social justice orientated approach. The ECJ is hovering between more factual protective and more normative fictitious conceptions of the consumer/worker. Despite these social justice elements, which 93 Micklitz, H.-W. (2009), ‘The Targeted Full Harmonisation Approach: Looking behind The Curtain’, in G. Howells and R. Schulze (eds), Modernising and Harmonising Consumer Contract Law, Munich: Sellier European Law Publishers, p. 47. 94 Caplovitz, D. (1967), The Poor Pay More, New York: Free Press. 95 As, Ayres, L. (1991), ‘Fair driving: Gender and Race Discrimination in Retail Car Negotiations’, Harvard Law Review, 104 (4), 817-871. 96 COM (2008) 614 final, p. 2. Hans-W. Micklitz 22 undoubtedly exist, I would, however, stress that the dominating Leitbild, the dominating normative construct in EU labour, anti-discrimination and consumer law is very much the normatively instrumentalised caricature of the real life world. It is the result of a market driven European ‘integration through (regulatory) law’. This understanding is far away from the starting point of social policies in the sixties and seventies, perhaps not so much from the changing patterns in the legal systems, but from political programmes of social welfare orientated Member States and even from early initiatives of the European Commission in the 1970s. The new modes of governance, so amply favoured by the European Commission in non-harmonised areas of EU labour law so as to foster social inclusion of those workers who incapable of keeping pace with the changing labour market, have no counterpart in consumer law. It does not even exist in areas such as services of general economic interests where the link to the OMC could easily be built to handle the situation of those customers who are excluded from basic services. OMC could serve, in theory, to approximate the different policies of the Member States and to define best practices concerning the protection of the vulnerable. 97 It has to be recalled that the regulatory mechanism established by the European Commission to design the ACQP and the DCFR resemble much more the New Approach on Technical Standards than the OMC which was promoted in the academic environment as an appropriate tool for the codification project. 98 That is why EU labour, anti- discrimination and consumer law are definitely and purposively different from national welfare state inspired protective concepts of the weaker parts of society. Secondly, the EU concept of justice differs from allocative libertarian concepts of justice, as EU labour, anti-discrimination and consumer law is in substance regulatory law which restricts not only the exercise of the market freedoms but also the private autonomy of parties to a labour and a consumer contract. None of the Treaty amendments and none of the secondary rules are inspired and guided by the idea that it is a prominent task for the European Union to establish and to ensure a European principle of freedom of contract and private autonomy. The ECJ has read such a principle into the four market freedoms. 99 The legal paradigm of EU law making via the Treaty and via secondary law, however, is regulatory law, this means regulated autonomy. The EU is transforming private law rules ‘from autonomy to functionalism in competition and regulation’. I have laid down my understanding of the role and function of European private law elsewhere. 100 EU regulatory labour and consumer law uses mandatory contract law rules as a device to achieve particular policy purposes which might be sector related or, as is the case in labour, anti-discrimination and consumer law, subject and sector related. All these mandatory EU rules on labour, anti- discrimination and consumer law are guided by one and the same philosophy, they are meant to bring the consumer and the worker into a legal position where she or he is equipped with the necessary set of rights so as to participate and reap the benefits of the Internal Market and the most competitive economy. EU regulatory law starts from the premise that a European Economic Constitution, based on the four market freedoms and competition law does not produce the necessary results by itself. 97 Bartl, M. (2010), ‘The Affordability of Energy. How much protection for the vulnerable consumer?’ Journal of Consumer Policy, 33 (2), 225-245; Neergard, U. (2008), ‘Services of General (Economic) Interest and the Services Directive -What Is Left Out, Why and Where to Go?’, in Neergard, U. and R. Nielsen and R.M. Roseberg (eds), The Services Directive, Consequences for the Welfare State in the European Social Model, Copenhagen: DJOF Publishing, p.65. 98 van Gerven, W. (2006), ‘Needed: A Method of Convergence for Private Law’, in A. Furrer (ed.), Europäisches Privatrecht, p. 437, on the parallel between the new approach and the making of the DCFR see Micklitz, H.-W. (2007), ‘(Selbst)-Reflektionen über die wissenschaftlichen Ansätze zur Vorbereitung einer europäischen Vertragsrechtskodifikation’, GPR Zeitschrift für Gemeinschaftsprivatrecht, p. 2. 99 See most recently, Basedow, J. (2007), ‘Party Autonomy in the Private International Law of Contracts’, European Review of Private Law, 15, 891. 100 I have developed this concept in H.-W. Micklitz (2009), ‘The Visible Hand of European Private Law’, in P. Eeckhout and T. Tridimas (eds.) (2010), Yearbook of European Law, 28, 3-60. Social Justice and Access Justice in Private Law Additional tools are needed to guarantee access to the market. This is exactly what the Lisbon Council, and since then various documents of the European Commission, mean when they constantly reiterate the formula of ‘reaping the benefits of the internal market’. Participation in and access to the internal market legitimises the adoption of mandatory EU labour, anti-discrimination and consumer law rules. Thirdly, the EU model of justice cannot and will not be equated with social justice, emanating from the workers’ movement that has developed in the 20th century. Nor will it be seen as a libertarian concept of justice where there is no statutory responsibility for the distribution of wealth between members of the society. So what is it then positively speaking? In German it would be Zugangsgerechtigkeit which literally means access justice. I found the term first in a document of the German Catholic Church which was prepared by eminent German academics as a response to the plea for transforming the German welfare state. Access justice alludes to the concept of ‘equity’ in the Common law system, not so much in its origins but in its content. Equity was meant to compensate for the deficiencies which resulted from the narrow and formalised rules on writs which restricted access to common law, whereas the regulatory law counterbalances the market freedoms. They share, however, the conviction that a legal system cannot be based on libertarian allocative concepts and that an element of ‘Billigkeit’ – equity – is needed that counterbalances such model. The EU legal system was originally designed as an international treaty before the ECJ transformed the Rome Treaty into a genuine legal order based on enforceable rights. EU regulatory labour and consumer law, right from its beginning and with constant support from the ECJ, could be understood not only as integrating a social dimension into the market based project of European integration, but also to make sure that those who should benefit from the mandatory rules are also given access to the legal system. In this sense, access justice contains two elements, first breaking down the barriers which limit participation and access and second strengthening the position of consumers and workers with a view to enforcing their rights. With regard to the first category, access justice would require that all market participants, including consumers, must have a fair and realistic chance to enter the market, consume its products and use its services, as well as reaping the benefits of the market. Access justice in the second sense relates to the degree of justice the individual might gain after he or she has been granted access. Rights are useless if they cannot be enforced. The ECJ is strongly advocating for judicial protection as now enshrined in Art. 47 of the Charter of Fundamental Rights. The EU is promoting, not only in the field of labour, anti-discrimination and consumer law, conflict resolution via mediation and dispute settlement outside courts. 101 In sum: access justice means more than a formal guarantee to workers and consumers that they may have a theoretical chance in participating in the market and reaping the benefits of the market. This would be justice in the meaning of the libertarian concept. Access justice in the meaning of Max Weber, quite to the contrary, materialises the equity doctrine. The legal system is responsible for establishing tools which transform the theoretical chance into a realistic opportunity, thereby eliminating all sorts of barriers which hinder the assertion of the claim to access. This requires further deepening. 5.2. The Two Constitute Elements: Access Rights and Anti-Discrimination Rights There are two major identifiable constitutive elements in which the European model of justice becomes visible: access ‘rights’ and non-discrimination ‘rights’. Both elements cut across labour and consumer law. They appear in labour and consumer law in different legal forms and different connotations, as ‘Leitnormen’ in the Lisbon Treaty, as part of the Charter of Fundamental Rights, in 101 See ECJ, 18.3.2010, Joined Cases C-317/08, C-318/08, C-319/08 and C-320/08 Alassini, ECR (2010) I- nyr. From a consumer point of view see Reich, N. in H.-W. Micklitz and P. Rott and N. Reich (2009), Understanding EU Consumer Law, Intersentia, § 8, p. 341. Hans-W. Micklitz 24 EU directives, recitals and recommendations. In its most outspoken form, they may grant individually enforceable rights, 102 vertically in consumer-worker state relationships, horizontally in consumer- worker private supplier-employer relationships, at least as long as the other party to the contract is tying the consumer-worker to collective private agreements which bear a quasi statutory character. In a less developed form, the so-called rights may formulate policy guidelines or mere policy objectives which could and should nevertheless be taken into account by the courts in the interpretation of the respective provisions that lie at the heart of the conflict. 103 The perspective I take is a private law perspective, meaning that I investigate the horizontal dimension of the two constitute principles, in order to design the possible impact on private law relations. 5.2.1. Specific Access Rights in Labour, Anti-Discrimination and Consumer Law In private law relations, the subjective rights inbuilt into the market freedoms as interpreted by the ECJ are paving the way for being granted access against discriminating collective private agreements. There are limits to this case-law since the ECJ does not submit collective private agreements to the scope of application of the four market freedoms. Otherwise, the logic of judicial control in unfair terms would have to be reconsidered. Herein there is a prominent field of collective private agreements that could easily be brought into the perspective of Bosman, Angonese, Olympique Marseille, Viking and Laval. But such an understanding would submit private law as such under the market freedom, a decision the ECJ refused to take in Alsthom Atlantique 104 and CMC Motorradcenter 105 . The Charter of Fundamental Rights does not contain an overall rule which grants access. However, there are bits and pieces in the Charter that can be broken down into the categories of labour and consumer law. Methodologically speaking, the Leitnormen of the Charter, the individually or collectively enforceable rights enshrined in the Charter, the policy objectives laid down in the Charter and the rights and objectives concretised in secondary Community law must be read and interpreted together. More recent EU regulations and directives refer, in their recitals, to the Charter of Fundamental Rights so as to ensure compliance of secondary Community law with the Charter. This is a most visible expression of the ongoing constitutionalisation process of private law relations. 106 (1) Labour: The Lisbon Treaty introduces a new Art. 2 which lays down a set of values common to the Member States: The Union is founded on the values of respect for human dignity, freedom, democracy, equality, the rule of law and respect for human rights, including the rights of persons belonging to minorities. These values are common to the Member States in a society in which pluralism, non- discrimination, tolerance, justice, solidarity and equality between women and men prevail. 102 I will not discuss the horizontal effect of these rights, as this would reach beyond the purpose of the paper. 103 See Kosta, V. (forthcoming 2010), ‘Internal Market Legislation and the Private Law of the Member States. The Impact of Fundamental Rights’, to be published in European Review of Contract Law. 104 ECJ C-339/89 ECR I–107. 105 ECJ C-93/92 ECR I-5009. 106 There is an abundant literature on this issue, see Brüggemeier G. and A. Ciacchi and G. Comandé (eds.) (2010), Fundamental Rights and Private Law in Europe, 1, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; Brüggemeier G. and A. Ciacchi and G. Comandé (eds.) (2010), Fundamental Rights and Private Law in Europe, 2, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; Cherednychenko, O. (2008), Fundament Rights, Contract Law and the Protection of the Weaker Party: A Comparative Analysis of the Constitutionalisation of the Contract Law with Emphasis on Risky Financial Transactions, doctoral dissertation – Utrecht University; Mak, Ch. (2008), Fundamental Rights in European Contract Law. A Comparision of the Impact of Fundamental Rights on Contractual Relationships in Germany, the Netherlands, Italy and England, Alphen aan den Rijin: Kluwer Law International. Social Justice and Access Justice in Private Law These values are not fully concretised in the established legal order. Therefore Art. 2 must be read as a Leitnorm, of no direct legal consequences. However, Art. 2, read together with the various articles of the EU Charter, might allow for the grounding of a European concept of justice on weighing social rights, e.g. those of workers and consumers balanced against the supplier’s right to market his or her products and services freely in and throughout the Internal Market. Chapter II formulates in Art. 14 the right to education and in Art. 15 the freedom to choose an occupation and the right to engage in work. Chapter IV defines, under the heading of solidarity, a whole set of rights, in particular Art. 27 (information and consultation), Art. 28 (collective bargaining), Art. 29 (access to placement services), Art. 30 (unjustified dismissal), Art. 31 (fair and just working conditions) and Art. 34 (social security). Access in labour law takes different forms, although there is at first sight a parallel to the services of general economic interests taking a broad understanding, i.e. under inclusion of financial and digital services. Since 1975, the EU has established a long standing policy to establish regulatory means which are aimed at keeping those workers in business who are in a more vulnerable position due to their particular personal circumstances, such as pregnant woman, parents, young people and part-time workers. However, in particular those measures taken under the Social Policy Agreement adopted under the Maastricht Protocol are reaching far beyond particular groups of workers and rather formulate access conditions for worker representation as well as for posting workers outside the home country. (2) consumers: Art. 38 of the Charter of Fundamental Rights requires that Union policy ensures a high level of protection. Individually enforceable rights cannot be deduced from Art. 38 of the Charter. The set of rights granted to consumers lag behind those granted to workers. Art. 35 (health care) and Art. 36 (access to services of general interests) provide for more specific protection in selected areas of consumer policy. The Treaty contains, in Art. 169 TFEU, elements of a ‘right to information’ 107 and a ‘right to establish consumer organisations’, although these rights have to be given shape via secondary community law in order to be understood as individual, maybe even enforceable, consumer rights. The most prominent feature in the Charter related to ‘access’ is to be found in Art. 36 which links access rights to the rather opaque concept of services of general economic interests: The Union recognises and respects access to services of general economic interests as provided for in national laws and practices, in accordance with the Treaty establishing the European Union, in order to promote the social and territorial cohesion of the Union. Art. 36 of the Charter is not meant to grant individual rights, at least not according to the majority of academic opinion. 108 Art. 36 of the Charter should, however, be read together with secondary legislation in the field of telecommunication, postal services, electricity, gas and transport, just to name those services which clearly come under the category of services of general economic interest. Legal doctrine argues that the respective directives are all united in the idea that the new consumer should and must have access to the new competitive market and that access must be understood as an individually enforceable right. 109 In Sabatauskas 110 , the ECJ did not decide on the right of access of 107 Radeideh, M. (2005), Fair Trading in EU Law – Information and Consumer Choice in the Internal Market, Groningen: Europa Law Publishing. 108 Regarding the interpretation of this provision and its doctrinal qualification see the contribution of Baquero Cruz in de Búrca, Gráinne (ed.) (2005), EU Law and the Welfare State: In Search of Solidarity, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 169 and 178. 109 Rott, P. (2005), ‘A new Social Contract Law for Public Services? – Consequences from Regulation of Services of General Economic Interests in the EC’, European Review of Contract Law, 1 (3), 323-345; Willet, C. (2008), ‘General Clauses on Fairness and the Promotion of Values Important in Services of General Interest’, in C. Twigg-Flesner and D. Parry and G. Howells and A. Nordhausen (eds.) (2008), in Yearbook of Consumer Law, p. 67. Hans-W. Micklitz 26 consumers to the Energy market. 111 Reading both the Charter and the respective directives together justifies the existence of an enforceable right of access to services of general economic interest. The addressee of such an individually enforceable right, however, would not be the supplier of the services of general economic interests but rather the respective Member State who is under an obligation to implement the directives in light of the Charter in a way that the customer is granted subjective enforceable rights. The missing horizontal direct effect has been subject to concern in academic circles for quite some time. The problematic effects of the existence of EU rights which can not be enforced against the correct addressee has been termed by N. Reich ‘Rights without Duties’ 112 . The Charter sheds new light on an old debate as is so amply demonstrated by the ECJ in Mangold and Kücükdevici. There is another equally difficult question pending. Can the right to access under Art. 36 be extended beyond the notion of services of general economic interest to the field of financial 113 and digital services 114 , to all those services on which the consumer-worker-citizen depends on today, economically and socially? From a doctrinal point of view, there is a huge gap in policy statements, like that in the 2000 Lisbon Council conclusions which builds concrete links beyond the SGEI stating that citizens may not be excluded from the benefits of the information society and that financial illiteracy should be combated. These announcements are neither reflected in the set of EU directives and regulations which govern the field of financial and digital services, nor in the Charter. The most concrete step the European Commission has taken comes from the field of financial services where the consumer shall be given a right to a bank account. However, the document has no binding legal effects. Again the Charter might allow for hardening soft law means. These types of services serve as perfect examples to demonstrate the difference between formal libertarian and materialised access under EU law. The simple chance to have access exists for particular groups of persons often only in theory. Materialised access requires more, it requests regulatory mechanisms which transform the theoretical normative opportunity into a realistic concrete perspective. The result of materialised access is not to be confounded with social justice. Social justice is result orientated. The outcome is what counts in order to be able to assess whether the result is just or not. Materialised access is less result orientated. It only establishes fair and non discriminatory access conditions. 5.2.2. The Horizontal Dimension of Anti-Discrimination The second constitutive element – anti-discrimination – is even wider spread and more deeply anchored in the Treaty, in the Charter and in secondary consumer and labour law rules. Contrary to access, which bears a positive, anti-discrimination bears a negative message. EU law prohibits various forms of discrimination, unequal payment in the Treaty for example and, since 2000, a wide variety of discriminatory practices related to the labour market but also practices which are not related to the (Contd.) 110 See on the right to access under Art. 20 of Directive 2003/54 in particular with regard to the right of access to universal services, ECJ C-239/07 Julius Sabatauskas, at 47, AG Kokott at 35, 38, nyr, with annotation Pirstner-Ebner, EuZW 2009, 15, 16 under 4. 111 See Rott, P. (2005), ‘A new Social Contract Law for Public Services? – Consequences from Regulation of Services of General Economic Interests in the EC’, European Review of Contract Law, 1 (3), 342. 112 Reich, N. (2010), ‘The public/private divide in European law’, in H.-M. Micklitz, and F. Cafaggi (eds.), European Private Law after the Common Frame of Reference, Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Publishing, p. 56. 113 Wilhelmsson, T. (2003), ‘Services of general interests and European Private law,’ in C. E. Rickett and T.G.W. Telfer (eds.), International Perspectives on Consumers’ Access to Justice, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, p. 149. 114 Micklitz, H.-W. and A. Oehler (2007), Consumer Policy in the Digital World, Scientific Advisory Board for Consumer, Food, and Nutrition Policies to the Federal Ministry of Consumer Protection, Food, and Agriculture, Germany, Berlin. Social Justice and Access Justice in Private Law labour market. The EU Charter deals extensively with non-discrimination in Art. 21, even in more detail than in the four Directives. The set of four Directives adopted in the aftermath of the Treaty of Amsterdam on the basis of Art. 13 (Art. 19 TFEU) and Art. 141 (3) (Art. 157 TFEU) extend the EU anti-discrimination rules beyond equal pay and equal access to employment to race and ethnic origin and – what is even more important in the context of the emerging EU model on justice – they establish anti-discrimination rules which are applicable outside the labour market in private law relations in the access to and the supply of goods and services. The so far academic debate turns, to a large extent, around the question on what kind of model of justice the anti-discrimination rules stand for. The debate gained pace through the insertion of the anti-discrimination principle into the ACQR and the DCFR. 115 I will borrow from Basedow 116 the distinction between integration motivated anti-discrimination verdicts and societal policy motivated anti-discrimination verdicts. This fits into the distinction between allocative libertarian and access justice/Zugangsgerechtigkeiten. Integration motivated anti- discrimination rules can be found in the above mentioned rules on regulated markets. The addressees of the anti-discrimination rules are Member States, regulatory authorities and the different economic actors. From a consumer/customer perspective they may be broken down in a) those indirectly affecting consumers and b) directly affecting them. Under the first category, we can note rules to ensure non-discriminatory access to the net, non-discriminatory tariffs for access to the network and rules meant to prohibit any form of non-discrimination between the different economic operators. Under the second category, particular rules on non-discriminatory treatment within the framework of universal service obligations can be noted. The societal policy motivated verdicts are of direct concern to workers and consumers. The basic philosophy of the non-discrimination rules has been developed by the ECJ within the framework of the Rome Treaty as accomplished by the two directives on equal pay and equal access to work. After a series of judgments where the ECJ was ready to give a broad reading to the notion of ‘pay’, in Smith v. Advel Systems 117 the ECJ rejected any attempt to use the Treaty provisions for levelling up equal pay. All that the Treaty requires is equal treatment of men and women, but not equal treatment at an equally high level. In the case at issue, EU law did not prevent the employer from raising the retirement age of women to that of men. This message can be transferred to all sorts of discrimination between men and women. 118 The EU rules on anti-discrimination allow for the establishment of equal access conditions, but the very same rules cannot be used to establish equal standards for men and women at the most favourable level. Those reading into the EU rules regarding standards of substantive justice in a redistributive meaning advocate for an EU model of justice which reaches beyond access justice. It might very well be that the proponents of such an interpretation will suffer from a renewed setback once the ECJ has to decide on the choice between social distributive and access justice. Such an understanding would not comply with Smith v. Advel and others, but it would be coherent with the philosophy of EU regulatory law. As the four Directives establish, only minimum standards would therefore remain for the Member States to decide whether they want to go beyond access justice within the national rules implementing the Directives. 115 Art. 3:101 to 3:103 ACQR and II.-2:01 to II.-2:103 DCFR. 116 Basedow, J. (2008), ‘Grundsatz der Nichtdiskriminierung,’ ZEuP, 237. 117 ECJ Case-408/92 ECR I-4435. 118 See Micklitz, H.-W. (2005), The Politics of Judicial Co-operation in the EU – the Case of Sunday trading, Equal Treatment and Good Faith, New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 182 and 188 with reference to the ECJ case law. Hans-W. Micklitz 28 Bibliography Adomeit, K. and H. Marcuse (2004), ‘Der Verbraucherschutz und das BGB’, Neue Juristische Wochenschrift, 579, 827-838. Adomeit, K. (1994), ‘Die gestörte Vertragsparität – ein Trugbild’, Neue Juristische Wochenschrift, 2467. Arendt, H. (1963), On Revolution, London: Penguin Books. Ayres, L. (1991), ‘Fair driving: Gender and Race Discrimination in Retail Car Negotiations’, Harvard Law Review, 104 (4), 817-871. Bartl, M. (2010), ‘The Affordability of Energy. How much protection for the vulnerable consumer?’, Journal of Consumer Policy, 33 (2), 225-245. Basedow, J. (2008), ‘Grundsatz der Nichtdiskriminierung’, ZEuP, 230-251. Basedow, J. (2007), ‘Party Autonomy in the Private International Law of Contracts’, European Review of Private Law, 15, 891. Bentham, J. [1798] (1907), An introduction to the principles of morals and legislation, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Berman, H.J. (1991), Recht und Revolution. Die Bildung der westlichen Rechtstradition, Frankfurt. Brüggemeier, G. (1977), Entwicklung des Rechts im organisierten Kapitalismus, Band 1: Von der Gründerzeit zur Weimarer Republik; (1979), Band 2: Vom Faschismus bis zur Gegenwart, Frankfurt: Sindicat. Calais-Auloy, J. (1984), ‘Collectively Negotiated Agreements: Proposed Reforms in France’, Journal of Consumer Policy, 7 (2), 115-123. Calliess, G.-W. and M. Renner (2009), ‘Between Law and Social Norms: The Evolution of Global Governance’, Ratio Juris, 22 (2), 260-280. Calliess, G.-P. (2003), ‘Nach der Schuldrechtsreform: Perspektiven des deutschen, europäischen und internationalen Verbrauchervertragsrechts’, 203, Archiv für die civilistische Praxis (AcP). Caplovitz, D. (1967), The Poor Pay More, New York: Free Press. Cartwright, J. and S. Vogenauer and S. Whittaker (eds) (2009), Reforming the French Law of Obligations, England: Hart Publishing. Cherednychenko, O. (2008), Fundament Rights, Contract Law and the Protection of the Weaker Party: A Comparative Analysis of the Constitutionalisation of the Contract Law with Emphasis on Risky Financial Transactions, doctoral dissertation – Utrecht University. Collins, H. (2009), ‘Lord Hoffmann and the Common Law of Contract’, European Review of Contract Law, 5 (4), 474-484. Countouris, N. (2009), ‘European Social Law as an Autonomous Legal Discipline,’ in P. Eeckhout and T. Tridimas (eds) (2009), Yearbook of European Law, 28, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Deakin, S. (2008), ‘Regulatory Competition after Laval’, Cambridge Yearbook of European Legal Studies, 10 (10), 581-610. de Búrca, Gráinne (ed.) (2005), EU Law and the Welfare State: In Search of Solidarity, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Social Justice and Access Justice in Private Law Dougan, M. (2009), ‘Minimum Harmonisation after Tobacco Advertising and Laval Un Partneri’, in M. Bulterman and L. Hancher and A. McDonnell and H. Sevenster (eds.), Views of European Law from the Mountain: Liber Amicorum Piet Jan Slot. Kluwer Law International. Eichengreen, B. (2007), The European Economy since 1945: Co-ordinateed Capitalism and Beyond, Princeton: Princeton University Press, NJF. Fauvarque-Cosson, B. and D. Mazeaud (ed.) (2008), European Contract Law: Materials for a Common Frame of Reference: Terminology, Guiding Principles, Model Rules, Munich: Sellier European Law Publishers. Flume, W. (2000), ‘Vom Beruf unserer Zeit für die Gesetzgebung’, Zeitschrift für Wirtschaftsrecht, 1727. Goode, R. (2001), ‘Insularity or Leadership? The Role of the United Kingdom in the Harmonisation of Commercial Law’, International and Comparative Law Quarterly, 50 (4), 751. Haar, B. and P. Copeland (2010), ‘What are the Future Prospects for the European Social Model?’, European Law Journal, 16 (3), 273-291. Haupt, H.-G. (1995), ‘Sozialpolitik und ihre gesellschaftlichen Grenzen in Frankreich vor 1914’, Jahrbuch für Wirtschaftsgeschichte, p. 171. Heiderhoff, B. (2004), Grundstrukturen des nationalen und europäischen Verbrauchervertrags-rechts, insbesondere zur Reichweite europäischer Auslegung, Habilitation- München. Hesselink, M.W. (2008), ‘CFR & social justice: a short study for the European Parliament on the values underlying the draft common frame of reference for European private law: what roles for fairness and social justice?, Centre for the Study of European Contract Law Working Paper Series No. 2008/04. Howells, G. and H.-W. Micklitz and T. Wilhelmsson (2006), European Fair Trading Law – The Unfair Commercial Practices Directive, Aldershot: Ashgate. Howells, G. and Weatherill, S. (2005), Consumer Protection Law, England: Ashgate Aldershot. James, L. (1994), The Rise and the Fall of the British Empire, London: Abacus. Kennedy, D. (2006) ‘Three Globalizations of Law and Legal Thought: 1850-2000’, in D. Kennedy, The New Law and Economic Development, Cambridge University Press. Kennedy, D. (2003), ‘Two Globalizations of Law & Legal Thought: 1850-1968’, Suffolk University Law Review, 36 (3), 631-679. Keßler, J. and H.-W. Micklitz (2008), ‘Kundenschutz auf den liberalisierten Märkten – Vergleich der Konzepte, Maßnahmen und Wirkungen in Europa – Personenverkehr/Eisenbahn,’ VIEW Schriftenreihe, Band 24. Keßler, J. and H.-W. Micklitz (2008), ‘Kundenschutz auf den liberalisierten Märkten – Vergleich der Konzepte, Maßnahmen und Wirkungen in Europa – Telekommunikation’, VIEW Schriftenreihe, Band 25. Kiesow, R.M. (2010), ‘Rechtswissenschaft – was ist das?’ JuristenZeitung, 586. Koopmans, T. (1991), ‘The Birth of European Law at the Cross Roads of Legal Traditions’, The American Journal of Comparative Law, 39 (3), 493. Kosta, V. (forthcoming 2010), ‘Internal Market Legislation and the Private Law of the Member States. The Impact of Fundamental Rights' to be published in European Review of Contract Law. Lord R. Goff (1997), ‘The Future of the Common Law’, International and Comparative Law Quarterly, 46 (4), 745. Hans-W. Micklitz 30 Mak, Ch. (2008), Fundamental Rights in European Contract Law. A Comparision of the Impact of Fundamental Rights on Contractual Relationships in Germany, the Netherlands, Italy and England, Alphen aan den Rijin: Kluwer Law International. Marella, M.R. (2006), ‘The Old and the New Limits to Freedom of Contract in Europe’, European Review of Contract Law, 2 (2), 264. Markesinis, B.S. (1994), ‘Learning from Europe and Learning in Europe’, in B. S. Markesinis (ed.), The Gradual Convergence: Foreign Ideas, Foreign Influences and English Law on the Eve of the 21st Century, p.1. Micklitz, H.-W. and F. Cafaggi (eds) (2010), The European Private Law after the Common Frame of References, Cheltenham: Edward Elgar Publishing. Micklitz, H.-W. (2009), ‘The Visible Hand of European Private Law’, in P. Eeckhout and T. Tridimas (eds) (2010), Yearbook of European Law, 29, 3-60. Micklitz, H.-W. and N. Reich (2009), “Crónica de una muerte anunciada: The Commission Proposal for a ‘Directive on Consumer Rights’ ”, Common Market Law Review, 46 (2), 471-519. Micklitz, H.-W. (2009), ‘Jack is out-of the Box - The efficient Consumer-Shopper’, in Wihelmsson, T. and J. Bärlund, Festschrift, JFT 3–4, 417–436. Micklitz, H.-W. (2009), ‘The Targeted Full Harmonisation Approach: Looking behind The Curtain’, in G. Howells and R. Schulze (eds), Modernising and Harmonising Consumer Contract Law, p. 47. Micklitz H.-W. and T. Roethe (2008), ‘ProdEnglandtsicherheit und Marktüberwachung im Ostseeraum – Rechtsrahmen und Vollzugspraxis’, VIEW Schriftenreihe, 26. Micklitz, H.-W. and P. Rott and L. Tichy (2007), Impact assessment of the revised proposal on consumer credit on the Member States legislation in Czech Republic, Germany and the United Kingdom, MS January 2007. Micklitz, H.-W. and A. Oehler (2007), Consumer Policy in the Digital World, Scientific Advisory Board for Consumer, Food, and Nutrition Policies to the Federal Ministry of Consumer Protection, Food, and Agriculture, Germany, Berlin. Micklitz, H.-W. (2005), The Politics of Judicial Co-operation in the EU – the Case of Sunday trading, Equal Treatment and Good Faith, New York: Cambridge University Press. Micklitz, H.-W. and T. Roethe and S. Weatherill (eds) (1994), Federalism and Responsibility - A study on Product Safety Law and Practice in the European Community, London: Graham & Trotmann. Micklitz, H.-W. and S. Weatherill (1993), ‘Consumer Policy in the European Union: Before and after Maastricht’, Journal of Consumer Policy Special Issue, 16 (3-4), 285-321. Münch, R. (2008), Die Konstruktion der europäischen Gesellschaft: zur Dialektik von transnationaler Integration und nationaler Desintegration, Frankfurt/Main: Campus-Verl. Neergard, U. (2008), ‘Services of General (Economic) Interest and the Services Directive -What Is Left Out, Why and Where to Go?’, in U. Neergard and R. Nielsen and R.M. Roseberg (eds), The Services Directive, Consequences for the Welfare State in the European Social Model, p.65. Radeideh, M. (2005), Fair Trading in EU Law – Information and Consumer Choice in the Internal Market, Groningen: Europa Law Publishing. Ramm, T. (1986), ‘Epilogue: The New Ordering of Labour Law’, in B. Hepple (ed.) (1986) The Making of Labour Law in Europe. A comparative Study of Nine Countries up to 1945, London: Mansell Publishing. Raulff, U. (ed.) (1987), Mentalitätengeschichte. Zur historischen RekonstrUktion geistiger Prozesse, Berlin. Social Justice and Access Justice in Private Law Reich, N. (2010), ‘The public/private divide in European law’, in H.-M. Micklitz and F. Cafaggi (eds.), European Private Law after the Common Frame of Reference, p. 56. Reich, N. in H.-W. Micklitz and P. Rott and N. Reich (2009), Understanding EU Consumer Law, Intersentia. Reich, N. (2006), ‘Protection of Consumers’ Economic Interests by EC Contract Law – Some Follow- up Remarks’, Sydney Law Review, 28 (1), 37-62. Rödl, F. (2009), ‘Europäische Arbeitsverfassung’ to be published in A. Bogdandy (ed.), Europäisches Verfassungsrecht, 2. Auflage. Rösler, H. (2004), Europäisches Konsumentenvertragsrecht: Grundkonzeption, Prinzipien und Fortentwicklung, Thesis Marburg. Rott, P. (2005), ‘A new Social Contract Law for Public Services? – Consequences from Regulation of Services of General Economic Interests in the EC’, European Review of Contract Law, 1 (3), 323- 345. Rust, U. and J. Falke (eds) (2007), AGG Allgemeines Gleichbehandlungsgesetz mit weiterführenden Vorschriften; Kommentar, Berlin: Schmidt. Säcker, F.J (2006), ‘Vertragsfreiheit und Schutz vor Diskriminierung’, ZEuP, 1ff. Schepel, H. (2007), ‘The European Brotherhood of Lawyers: The Reinvention of Legal Science in the Making of European Private Law’, Law and Social Inquiry, 32 (1), 183-199. Schulin, E. (1969), Handelsstaat England. Das politische Interesse der Nation im Außenhandel vom 16. bis ins frühe 18. Jahrhundert, reprinted in The American Historical Review (1975), 80 (1), 107. Schulze, H. (1985), ‘Mentalitätsgeschichte – Chancen und Risiken eines Paradigmas der franzö- sischen Geschichtswissenschaft’, Geschichte in Wissenschaft und Unterricht, 36, 247-270. Social Justice Study Group (2004), ‘Social Justice in European Contract Law: A Manifesto’, European Law Journal, 10 (6), 653-674. Teubner, G. (1999-2000), Ein Fall von strUktureller Korruption? Die Familienbürgschaft in der Kollision unverträglicher Handlungslogiken, Kritische Vierteljahreszeitschrift für Gesetzgebung und Rechtswissenschaft. Thibaut, A.F.J. and F.C. v Savigny [1973] (2002), Ihre programmatischen Schriften, mit einer Einfüh- rung von Hans Hattenhauer, München. Schepel, H. (2007), ‘The European Brotherhood of Lawyers: The Reinvention of Legal Science in the Making of European Private Law’, Law and Social Inquiry, 32 (1), 183- 199. Schwintowski, H-P. (1996), Recht und Gerechtigkeit. Eine Einführung in Grundfragen des Rechts,1, Berlin: Springer-Lehrbuch. Vandenberghe, A.-S. (2007), ‘The Economics of the Non-Discrimination Principle in General Contract Law’, European Review of Contract Law, 3 (4), 420. van Gerven, W. (2006), ‘Needed: A Method of Convergence for Private Law’, in A. Furrer (ed.), Europäisches Privatrecht, p. 437. Walker, N. (2006), ‘Big ‘C’ or Small ‘c’?’, European Law Journal, 12 (1), 12-14. Walker, N. (2005), ‘Legal Theory and the European Union: A 25th Anniversary Essay’, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, 25 (4), 581-601. Weatherill, S. (2009), ‘Competence and Legitimacy,’ in C. Barnard and O. Odusu, The Outer Limits of European Union Law, UK: Hart Publishing. Hans-W. Micklitz 32 Weatherill, S. (2005), ‘Minimum Harmonisation as Oxymoron? The Case of Consumer Law’, in H.- W. Micklitz (ed.), Verbraucherrecht in Deutschland – Stand und Perspektiven, VIEW Schriftenreihe, Band 20. Weatherill, S. (1996), ‘The Evolution of European Consumer Law and Policy: From well Informed Consumer to Confident Consumer’, in H.-W. Micklitz (ed.), Rechtseinheit oder Rechtsvielfalt in Europa?, Baden-Baden: Nomos, p. 423. Weber, M. [1922] 1980, Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft. Grundriß der verstehenden Soziologie, Tubingen: J.C.B. Mohr. Whincup, M. (1980), Consumer Legislation in the United Kingdom and the Republic of Ireland, New York. Wieacker, F. (1967), Privatrechtsgeschichte der Neuzeit, 2. Auflage, Göttingen. Wilhelmsson, T. (2008), ‘The Contract Law Acquis: Towards More Coherence Through Generalisation?’, Europäischer Juristentag, 4 (1), 111-145. Wilhelmsson, T. (2005), ‘European Consumer Law: Theses on the Task of the Member States’, in H.- W. Micklitz (ed.), Verbraucherrecht in Deutschland – Stand und Perspektiven, VIEW Schriftenreihe, Band 20. Wilhelmsson, T. (2003), ‘Services of general interests and European Private law,’ in Rickett, C. E. and T. G.W. Telfer (eds.), International Perspectives on Consumers’ Access to Justice, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Willet, C. (2008), ‘General Clauses on Fairness and the Promotion of Values Important in Services of General Interest’, in C. Twigg-Flesner and D. Parry and G. Howells and A. Nordhausen (eds.), in Yearbook of Consumer Law. Zimmermann, R. (2005), ‘Consumer Contract Law and General Contract Law: The German Experience’, Legal Current Problems, 58, 415-489. work_ie2xba3l5nbo3dx3tpc2tdfjoy ---- wp-p1m-38.ebi.ac.uk Params is empty 404 sys_1000 exception wp-p1m-38.ebi.ac.uk no 221732773 Params is empty 221732773 exception Params is empty 2021/04/06-03:20:30 if (typeof jQuery === "undefined") document.write('[script type="text/javascript" src="/corehtml/pmc/jig/1.14.8/js/jig.min.js"][/script]'.replace(/\[/g,String.fromCharCode(60)).replace(/\]/g,String.fromCharCode(62))); // // // window.name="mainwindow"; .pmc-wm {background:transparent repeat-y top left;background-image:url(/corehtml/pmc/pmcgifs/wm-nobrand.png);background-size: auto, contain} .print-view{display:block} Page not available Reason: The web page address (URL) that you used may be incorrect. Message ID: 221732773 (wp-p1m-38.ebi.ac.uk) Time: 2021/04/06 03:20:30 If you need further help, please send an email to PMC. Include the information from the box above in your message. Otherwise, click on one of the following links to continue using PMC: Search the complete PMC archive. Browse the contents of a specific journal in PMC. Find a specific article by its citation (journal, date, volume, first page, author or article title). http://europepmc.org/abstract/MED/ work_ieubcl43ebhgtbqpp7eirkjcum ---- Microsoft Word - Access_to_Justice_and_Litigation_Saraceno_SSRN WP UvA-DARE is a service provided by the library of the University of Amsterdam (https://dare.uva.nl) UvA-DARE (Digital Academic Repository) Justice: greater access, lower costs Saraceno, M. DOI 10.2139/ssrn.2383864 Publication date 2014 Document Version Submitted manuscript Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): Saraceno, M. (2014). Justice: greater access, lower costs. (Amsterdam Center for Law & Economics Working Paper; No. 2014-01). University of Amsterdam. https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2383864 General rights It is not permitted to download or to forward/distribute the text or part of it without the consent of the author(s) and/or copyright holder(s), other than for strictly personal, individual use, unless the work is under an open content license (like Creative Commons). Disclaimer/Complaints regulations If you believe that digital publication of certain material infringes any of your rights or (privacy) interests, please let the Library know, stating your reasons. In case of a legitimate complaint, the Library will make the material inaccessible and/or remove it from the website. Please Ask the Library: https://uba.uva.nl/en/contact, or a letter to: Library of the University of Amsterdam, Secretariat, Singel 425, 1012 WP Amsterdam, The Netherlands. You will be contacted as soon as possible. Download date:06 Apr 2021 https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2383864 https://dare.uva.nl/personal/pure/en/publications/justice-greater-access-lower-costs(00b3b774-53f0-42f3-9667-aec2be978011).html https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2383864 Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2383864 JUSTICE: GREATER ACCESS, LOWER COSTS Margherita Saraceno Amsterdam Law School Legal Studies Research Paper No. 2014-06 Amsterdam Center for Law & Economics Working Paper Paper No. 2014-01 Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2383864 Justice: Greater Access, Lower Costs Margherita Saraceno♣ January 21, 2014 Abstract Litigation imposes large costs on society; this justifies settlement considerations. In any case, access to justice is critical to socioeconomic development; as such, it needs to be balanced with litigation minimization. This study examines the tradeoff between litigation and access to justice and explicitly elucidates their relationship. In considering access issues, this study finds that the outcomes of policies that affect parties’ litigation decisions partially depart from those in the standard literature. For instance, increasing parties’ litigation costs does not necessarily promote settlement in the shadow of the court. Rather, effects depend on the elasticity of the demand for legal remedies. Furthermore, even while pushing litigation, enhancing access to justice is efficient as long as the claimant’s marginal propensity to litigate is smaller than the social opportunity-cost of access to justice. This finding offers further insight into the suitability of litigation subsidization through legal aid. JEL classification: K41. Keywords: access to justice, litigation, settlement, elasticity. _____________________________________________________________________ ♣Amsterdam Center for Law and Economics, University of Amsterdam and DEMS, University of Milano- Bicocca. Roetersstraat 11, 1018 WB Amsterdam, Netherlands. Phone: +31 (0)20 525 7164; Fax: +31 (0)20 525 5318; Email: m.saraceno@uva.nl. Corresponding author. This research has received funding from the People Programme (Marie Curie Actions) of the European Union's Seventh Framework Programme (FP7/2007-2013) under REA grant agreement n° 298470. I wish to thank Giuseppe Dari-Mattiacci, Iljoong Kim, Eric Langlais, Avraham Tabbach, Josephine van Zeben, Abraham L. Wickelgren, and the participants of the AEDE Conference 2013 (Granada), the CLEA Conference 2013 (Toronto), the GLEA Conference 2013 (Lugano), and the LIEN-Nanterre seminar (Paris) for the useful suggestions. The usual disclaimers apply. Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2383864 1   1. Introduction Disputes naturally emerge in every complex society. All of the parties to a dispute are directly affected by the events that gave rise to such dispute, and thus, they all tend to be interested in resolving them. However, disputes and their resolution are not purely private problems; they also constitute a social problem, as unresolved disputes produce negative externalities for the whole of society. In fact, when claimants simply “give up” because legal remedies are for some reason inaccessible, major social consequences emerge, including a sense of impunity, a lack of trust in institutions, underdeterrence, and increased uncertainty within the legal system. In extreme situations, when legal remedies are missing or inaccessible, conflicts can lead to severe consequences for the parties involved; widespread disorder and even violence can arise. Conversely, when access to justice is guaranteed, justiciable problems can be resolved through legal remedies such as in-court litigation or settlement (in a broad sense). For these reasons, effective and full access to justice is considered a crucial element in socioeconomic development and social security. Even the most developed legal systems struggle with ensuring citizens access to justice, since a significant number of claimants continue to be systematically excluded from legal remedies. (See, for example, the Access to Justice Initiative by the U.S. Department of Justice, the Initiative in Support of Access to Justice by the Department of Justice of Canada, the Australian Government Strategic Framework for Access to Justice, and the Access to Justice Agenda by the European Union Agency for Fundamental Rights.) Besides access to justice, policymakers have highlighted a further problem related to dispute resolution. In-court litigation is extremely costly for society, and excessive amounts of litigation result in judicial diseconomies and increased court workloads, eventually exacerbating inefficiencies. Despite the dearth of internationally comparable indicators concerning public expenditure vis-à-vis the judiciary, the public budget allocated to the various justice systems remains relevant.1 Policymakers are acutely aware of the need to ensure, and in some cases enhance, access to justice while keeping judiciary costs low. This problem is aggravated by the need to curb public spending in a time of financial crisis, since litigation accounts for most of the judicial spending. The academic literature usually analyzes these two problems—namely, obstacles to access to justice, and excessive litigation—separately, despite their evident interconnections. This study attempts to overcome this shortcoming in the literature by taking a unitary approach to the relationship between litigation and access to justice.                                                              1 For instance, in 2010, the annual approved budget allocated to the judiciary in the United States was USD 6.8 billion; across the European Union, the per-country average was EUR 2.8 billion, with a maximum of EUR 14.2 billion in the United Kingdom and a minimum of EUR 0.08 billion in Cyprus. Data are not directly comparable, since budgets can include a variety of statements depending on the country. See the Administrative Office of the U.S. Courts (2012) and CEPEJ (2012). 2   Starting from a standard law and economics setting (Bebchuk 1984; Nalebuff 1987), the problem of dispute resolution is modeled from both the micro perspective (i.e., parties’ choices) and the aggregated perspective of the social planner. The resulting framework allows us to analyze how policies—including administrative fees related to going to court, additional penalties and punitive damages, and legal aid—affect access to justice, litigation, and finally, the social costs of dispute resolution. The main results of this study can be summarized as follows. Dispute selection for trial. Taking into account the dimension of access to justice, the model used herein reconsiders some of the usual results found in the law and economics literature on litigation and the settlement rate. In particular, we find that higher claimant litigation costs discourage both settlement and litigation. Actually, every claimant who “gives up” because of excessive litigation cost neither settles nor litigates. Increasing the value at stake ambiguously affects settlement because of two combined effects: some claims shift from the sample of those settled to the sample of those litigated; others start to be settled, rather than remain unresolved. Finally, in some circumstances, the defendant costs play no role in determining the type of legal solution that is actually adopted. In particular, when the claimant must bear litigation costs that are relatively higher than those of the defendant, the selection of the preferred legal solution is driven mainly by the former. For claims in the shadow of the court, the model shows that changes in costs and amounts at stake affect settlement and litigation rates, depending on the elasticity of the demand for legal remedies. Litigation and access to justice. Improving access to justice will necessarily increase the number of litigation instances; this raises a relevant policy tradeoff. However, guaranteeing the access to justice of socially meritorious claims, even at the cost of pushing litigation, is always efficient. Intuitively, thanks to settlement, one additional claim’s access to justice results in less than one additional claim in litigation. Therefore, it is efficient to improve access to justice, as long as the claimant’s marginal propensity to litigate remains smaller than the social opportunity-cost of access to justice. Policy implications. The model used herein illustrates the tradeoff between promoting access to justice and discouraging litigation, through policies that result in larger litigation costs for claimants or an increased amount at stake (e.g., punitive damages). Additional penalties and fees levied on the defendant can be either wholly effective or ineffective, depending on the economic involvement of the defendant in the lawsuit. In particular, such policies can discourage litigation without affecting access to justice, except when the defendant must bear litigation costs that are so low that the decision to litigate or settle is in fact driven by the claimant. With respect to legal aid, the model shows that it is efficient to subsidize litigation as long as the standardized rate of litigation is lower than the social opportunity- costs of access to justice. 3   The remainder of this paper is organized as follows. Section 2 provides a brief overview of the literature. Section 3 presents the model and its policy implications, with particular attention being devoted to legal aid. Section 4 provides concluding remarks. 2. Background and related literature This section attempts to summarize briefly the main literature contributions, an understanding of which can be useful in framing the potential tradeoff between litigation and access to justice. Most studies generally focus either on litigation dynamics or on access to justice. The former topic constitutes a broad strand of law and economics literature, while the latter has mainly been investigated from either a comparative law or a political economy perspective. 2.1. Litigation versus settlement (in the shadow of the court) The traditional literature on litigation and settlement bargaining is vast and mainly based on a game-theory approach. A more recent and comprehensive survey of this topic is provided by Daughety and Reinganum (2012), who systematize a large number of contributions ranging from axiomatic models to those based on a strategic approach.2 Mainly, this kind of literature analyzes the reasons why parties in conflict fail in their negotiations and, subsequently, their cases go in trial. In fact, settlement acts as a sort of filter by selecting some of the cases for the court while resolving the others. Although litigation is able to produce positive externalities in terms of deterrence and reductions in law- uncertainty through precedent,3 it is generally considered wasteful, both for the parties involved and for society. For this reason, the literature mainly focuses on the capacity of bargaining to reduce the litigation rate.4 Pretrial bargaining has been modeled both as a sequential game (with one, multiple, or infinite rounds) and, less frequently, as a simultaneous game.5 According to the literature, the main source of settlement breakdown and consequent litigation is the persistence of the differential expectations of the parties on trial outcomes, even after bargaining interaction.6 This persistence has been explained while                                                              2 Axiomatic models usually assume perfect or imperfect but symmetric information. Solutions are typically cooperative. Strategic models emphasize the strategic interaction of parties, the Bayesian updating of their beliefs, and noncooperative solutions. See Cooter and Rubinfeld (1989). 3 See Che and Yi (1993); Dari-Mattiacci and Daffeins (2007); Landes (1971); Polinsky and Rubienfeld (1988); Posner (1973); and Shavell (1982), (1997), and (1999). 4 Besides the literature on settlement, see also contributions vis-à-vis alternative dispute resolution (e.g., Shavell 1995). 5 Settlement is often designed as an ultimatum game in one round, as seen in, for example, Bebchuk (1984), P’ng (1983), and Reinganum and Wilde (1986). On multiple-round settlement, see Spier (1992) and Wang et al. (1994). On infinite rounds, see Rubinstein (1982) and Yildiz (2003). On simultaneous games, see Daughety and Reinganum (1993) and Friedman and Wittman (2006). 6 In her extensive survey, Spier (2007) summarizes further explanations of settlement failure, including indivisible claims, nonpecuniary gains from going to trial, friction in the liability system, and the existence of multiple claimants. 4   assuming either different and inconsistent priors (typically in axiomatic models), or asymmetric information between litigants (in strategic models).7  A common lesson can be drawn from the broad array of specific models on settlement: both asymmetries between parties in terms of information or beliefs and low litigation costs give rise to a positive rate of litigation, and then a certain level of inefficiency owing to some use of a costly trial. From this perspective, any model that is designed as a one-sided, asymmetric-information ultimatum game seems to provide sufficiently robust and general insights (Daughety and Reinganum 2012, section 12.4).  Although the theoretical literature on settlement is immense, a great proportion of the studies therein assume that the claimant has a credible threat to litigate against the defendant. This means that the claimant can and wants to go to trial if settlement fails. In modeling, the capacity and will to proceed to court usually correspond to the fact that the claimant is, somehow, always able to pay for litigation and expects to obtain a positive expected value (PEV) from it. This common assumption is perhaps related to the fact that there is little consensus on how to distinguish socially meritorious lawsuits from those that are frivolous. Although resolving claims with negative expected value (NEV) may be socially valuable, the literature tends not to distinguish NEV cases and frivolous suits.8  Relatively few contributions relax the PEV hypothesis, and Schwartz and Wickelgren (2009) show that the game design strongly affects the possibility of settling NEV cases that will typically remain neither settled nor litigated.9  In a nutshell, the principal interest of the theoretical literature on litigation dynamics seems to be explaining failures of settlement in the shadow of the court—namely, when claimants can at least accomplish a legal remedy through a trial. This approach has generated a rich body of literature on procedural rules and settlement protocols that can influence case selection and hence the settlement rate.10 However, the standard literature seems to place little emphasis on the fact that in the real world many people cannot achieve any legal remedy, because they are unable to be in the shadow of the court.                                                               7 See Bar-Gill (2005), Cooter and Rubinfeld (1994), Gould (1973), Landes (1971), Priest and Klein (1984), and Posner (1973). See Chung (1996) about inconsistent priors. See also Gertner and Miller (1995), who provide a settlement protocol where divergent priors cannot be perfectly communicated and thus remain private information. Starting with P’ng (1983), a strategic approach involving the updating of consistent beliefs has been preferred in analyses of the strategies of rational agents. 8 On the distinction between PEV and NEV cases and meritorious and frivolous cases, see Bebchuk and Chang (1996, p. 372), Katz (1990, p. 3), Nalebuff (1987, FN 3), Polinsky and Rubinfeld (1993, p. 404), Shavell (1982), and Spier (2007). 9 They show that claimants with NEV cases are unable to settle their claims. Conversely, defendants can also resist litigation when they have an NEV defense. Other studies show that NEV claims can be settled in very specific cases: i) in screening models with uninformed defendants (Bebchuk 1988), ii) by making particular assumptions concerning legal costs (Bebchuk 1996, Katz 1990, and Rosemberg and Shavell 1985); and iii) by assuming a claimant’s commitment to proceed, even if his or her updated expected value is negative (Nalebuff 1987). 10 Reviewing this literature is beyond the scope of the current study. Some extensive surveys are available, including those of Daughety and Reinganum (2012), Hay and Spier (2002), and Spier (2007). 5   Besides the theoretical literature, several empirical contributions analyze dispute selection for trial. While theory helps us recognize that the cases that go to trial are filtered by settlement, the empirical literature provides evidence of this phenomenon. However, econometrics offers a very multifaceted picture of the determinants of settlement rate. On the other hand—and probably for data-reliability reasons—the empirical literature on settlement and trial also focuses on cases in the shadow of the court—namely, those that are typically already filed and then legally resolved, by either settlement or trial.11   Finally, the literature on dispute selection for trial apparently does not address the fact that some disputes are not resolved at all, by litigation or by settlement. Since cases where claimants surrender are simply excluded from the analysis, litigation represents a failure because settlement is almost always cheaper (for both the parties involved and for society) and more expeditious than a trial.   2.2. Access to justice The interest in settlement (and in other pre- or extra-judicial solutions) is overriding, especially in developed countries where the primary impression is that the average citizen has too much access to justice.12 In such cases, litigation is perceived as excessive, and the judiciary is costly for taxpayers, the courts are overloaded by an increasing backlog, and consequently the length of proceedings is often too long to be accounted for in the quality of sentencing. For instance, among European Union countries, the average public budget allocated to courts in 2010 was EUR 66 per capita (including public prosecution and legal aid) (CEPEJ 2012). Even though the productivity and efficiency of the courts has improved in some cases, in some countries, the length of proceedings remains impressively protracted. (In Italy, the average duration of a litigious divorce at the first-instance court was 538 days; in Spain, robbery cases have an average duration of 826 days.)13 In 2010, in the United States, the per-capita budget for the judiciary was about USD 22 (without including several items, such as legal aid). In the United States in that year, the problem of heavy caseloads is relevant, as the median of the duration of complex civil proceedings exceeded 687 days.14 Nonetheless, as has been asserted by several institutional contributions to the literature—including the most recent of FRA (2011) and CFCJ (2012)—and by the U.S. Department of Justice (2013), in the most advanced judicial systems, access to justice is critical. The U.S. Department of Justice, in fact, “established the Access to Justice Initiative (ATJ) in March 2010 to address the access-to-justice crisis                                                              11 See Cooter et al. (1982), Hylton and Lin (2010), and Priest and Klein (1984). See also Eisembergh (1990) and Fournier and Zuehlke (1989), each of whom suggest some testable models of settlement and case selection. On the possible determinants of settlement rates and success rates in trials, see Boyd and Hoffman (2012), Farber and White (1991), Gross and Syverud (1991), Huang et al. (2010), and Kessler et al. (1996). 12 See the extensive work of Rhode (2004), and also that of Ramseyer and Rasmusen (2010) and Silver (2002). 13 See CEPEJ (2012); the data refer to first-instance noncriminal courts. 14 Statistics are provided by the Administrative Office of the U.S. Courts on the institutional website. Duration refers to the median time interval in 2010 among civil cases, from filing to trial. 6   in the [American] criminal and civil justice system” (quoted from the ATJ ). Many common people are unable to access the judiciary, often for financial reasons, but there are also other barriers. Some of them decide to seek out unconventional solutions, while others simply give up.15 Despite awareness that access to justice is problematic, information about the extent of the problem, its determinants, and possible solutions remains fragmented. Although financial obstacles do not constitute the sole cause of unmet legal needs, academic contributions have mainly focused on the private costs of litigation.16 Not surprisingly, the most frequently debated of the policies used to address limited access to justice is that pertaining to litigation through legal aid. Recently, new actions like third-party litigation-funding and legal services deregulation have been suggested as ways of making litigation more affordable.17 From a socioeconomic perspective, access to justice has become a fundamental issue, and not only for reasons of fairness.18 Effective access to the judiciary is a leading component of a democratic society.19 Political economics has widely demonstrated—mainly empirically—the positive interdependence of economic and legal institutions. In particular, both adjudication and law enforcement through the courts and well-functioning legal institutions are critical to social and economic growth, since inequalities in terms of rights protections can cause institutional breakdowns and slow growth.20 In general, a lack of access to legal remedies should be a concern not only for those individuals who are unable to pursue their claims; it should be the concern of all citizens, as it affects the health and economic and social well-being of all. The tendency among unresolved disputes (especially in some areas of law) is for there to be an escalation in conflicts, which make resolution more and more difficult. Legal issues such as family matters, injuries from accident and crime, housing and                                                              15 See Coumarelos et al. (2006); Currie (2006), (2009a), and (2009b); Genn (1999); Kritzer (2008); and Rohde (2004). See also the following surveys: AM. BAR ASS’N (1994) and LEGAL SERVS. CORP. (2005) and (2009), with regard to the United States; Genn (1999), with regard to the United Kingdom; and Genn and Paterson (2001), with regard to Scotland. 16 On the obstacles to access to justice, see Genn (1999); Yates et al. (2001); and Kritzer (2008) and (2010). For a development perspective, see UNDP (2004) and (2010) and World Bank (2006). For a theoretical perspective, see also Galanter (2010), Fennel (2010), and Mnookin (1993). On the role of costs, see Buck et al. (2009); Hadfield (2000), (2009), and (2010); and Kritzer (2008) and (2010). 17 See Hodges et al. (2009). On legal aid, see Buchko et al. (2002), Garoupa and Stephen (2004), and Varano and De Luca (2007). Statistics on legal aid in European countries are found in CEPEJ (2012). On third-party litigation funding, see Daffein and Desrieux (2011), Fenn and Rickman (2010), Garber (2010), Molot (2010), and Rodak (2006). On the debate on the market organization of legal services, see Garupa (2013) and Hadfield (2000), (2008), and (2013). 18 Legal scholars have extensively debated the relevance of access to justice as a right that underpins all other rights. See Cappelletti et al. (1979) and Schlesinger (1988), each of whom provide seminal contributions on this topic. See also Alcock (1976), Mattei (2006), and Sommerlad (2004). 19 See Friedman (2006), Marshall (1950), UNDP (2010), and World Bank (2006). 20 See Acemoglu and Johnson (2005), Ellickson (1991), and North (1989). See also Glaeser et al. (2003) and UNDP (2010). 7   employment, fundamental rights like nondiscrimination and health, and disputes with public administrations can exacerbate both social exclusion and overall social costs.21 Scholars have recognized the potential tensions between effective access to justice for all, and the social and private costs related to litigation (Posner 1998; Shavell 1982). However, the theoretical law and economics literature barely works to disentangle the emerging tradeoff between favoring access to justice and curbing expensive litigation. Societies could reduce litigation costs dramatically by discouraging the use of the courts, but if this gives rise to numerous unresolved justiciable problems, its burden on socioeconomic development may be substantial. 3. The Model Given the relevance of the potential tradeoff between litigation and access to justice, the model below addresses the question of dispute resolution, from both private and social perspectives. 3.1. The social planner’s problem From an aggregated perspective, the “social planner’s problem” can be defined as follows. Disputes are assumed to be exogenously determined and can be resolved legally by litigation in court, or by settlement.22 Otherwise, disputes remain unresolved because claimants give up —or, they are resolved by unconventional means, including violence.  Litigation (l) is costly for society. Assume that, on average, resolving a dispute by litigation costs the taxpayers λ. This references the idea that litigation involves a transfer from litigants to the public administration and also that a net negative externality arises.  Alternatively, disputes can be resolved by settlement (s). This system of dispute resolution is assumed not to be costly for society. Otherwise, since settlement is simply less costly than litigation, the social cost of settlement is normalized to zero.  Finally, if disputes remain unresolved or are resolved by unconventional means ( ), the society bears a social cost that relates to the lack of legal solutions. The social cost of includes costs related to reduced social cohesion, diminished security, lower trust, a reduced sense of justice, underdeterrence, social exclusion, morbidity, and violence. On average, an unresolved/unconventionally resolved dispute costs society γ.                                                              21 See Genn (1999); Pleasence et al. (2004), (2006), (2007), and (2008); and Stratton and Anderson (2008). 22 Considerations of endogenous disputes would complicate our analysis, without being overly useful. J J 8   The total number of disputes is normalized to 1, without a loss of generality. Assuming that each “resolution” occurs with a certain probability, the social planner’s problem may correspond to the minimization of the following social loss function: It is evident that the first-best solution for the social planner would be that all disputes be resolved by settlement, with zero social costs. Nonetheless, two main points need to be noted. First of all, even if every dispute were settled (or in general, legally resolved out of court), a court-based system nonetheless needs to be guaranteed. Settlement can exist only as a complement to litigation, since the latter represents the last-resort mechanism in making bargaining agreements enforceable. Conversely, litigation requires no party’s agreement to work, since the winning party achieves an enforceable solution against the other party. Second, by setting procedural rules and the judiciary, the social planner can define the supply for legal solutions (both l and s). Note that in developed legal systems, the supply of legal remedies may be seen as perfectly elastic, at least in the short term. In fact, legal systems do not admit to rationing the supply of legal solutions to justiciable problems. Actually, for a given level of quality or fairness, a less- efficient judiciary can provide legal remedies at a higher cost and with longer delays, while efficient courts can provide solutions at a lower cost and more quickly. However, the social planner cannot directly determine how disputes are actually resolved. This choice in fact rests on how the parties in a conflict decide to resolve their justiciable conflicts. Therefore, to analyze the social planner’s problem, it is necessary to disentangle how the parties work to resolve it. 3.2. The parties’ problem From a micro perspective, the analysis focuses on a representative claimant–defendant pair that is involved in a (monetary) dispute. Both claimant K and defendant Δ are rational and risk-neutral.  The claim amount at stake is A; it is common and public knowledge. This is also the value that is awarded by the court in favor of K, and paid by Δ, if the former prevails in trial because the latter is recognized as liable by the judge. No judicial error can occur over both the magnitude of the claim and the liability of the defendant.  To litigate before the court, K bears a litigation cost CK = cKA, where cK ∈ 0,1 . Actually, rational K never proceeds to trial for cK ≥ 1. If called before the court for trial, Δ must pay a litigation cost equal to CΔ = cΔA, where cΔ ∈ 0,1 . Each party bears his/ her own litigation cost. Litigation costs are public and common knowledge; they include lawyers’ and court fees, taxes, and all the other costs that are privately borne by parties to    Pr Pr 0 Prl s J      9   litigate in court. As commonly assumed in the literature, settlement allows parties to save on litigation costs. The assumption that costs are proportional to the amount at stake is without loss of generality. Furthermore, litigation costs relate largely to the amount at stake rather than, for instance, the actual liability of the defendant (Trubek et al. 1983). In this subsection, no budget constraint restricts the parties’ choices; in subsection 3.4., a budget constraint is introduced for the claimant.  The interaction between the parties is characterized by one-sided asymmetric information concerning the liability of the defendant.23 In particular, K is the uninformed party,  while Δ in the informed party. K does not know if Δ is of a type that will be considered actually liable (type 1) or not (type 0); she only knows that the probability of facing a liable defendant (Δ₁) and prevailing in trial is p, while the probability of facing a nonliable defendant (Δ₀) and losing the case is (1 – p). Δ knows his own type. Note that p can be interpreted as the legal merit of the case. For the sake of simplicity, we assume that the defendant is either fully liable or not liable. This facilitates the interpretation of results, without loss of generality. As explained in subsection 2.1., one- sided asymmetric information models provide a litigation-settlement framework that is sufficiently robust to catch the many insights concerning the parties’ behavior. Since the study focuses on the access-to-justice problem for claimants, the preferred option is to assume that K is the uninformed party. 3.2.1. Access to justice and settlement bargaining Once the dispute arises, if K simply gives up and the dispute remains unresolved, she will not obtain any kind of relief, and both parties will have a null payoff.24 If K expects a positive outcome from litigation, she will access the judiciary and file a case against Δ. However, before the actual trial commences, it is appropriate to attempt a settlement, to avoid litigation costs. Consistent with some of the literature and without any original contribution from the perspective of the settlement process, bargaining is designed as an ultimatum-screening game (Bebchuk 1984; Nalebuff 1987). This allows for understanding several features of trial selection while being functional with regard to the analysis. In particular, the uninformed party—in this case, K—proposes a take-or- leave-it agreement to the informed party—namely, Δ. The take-or-leave-it bid for settlement implies that K commits to going in trial in the case of settlement failure—even if, after bargaining, the expected value of litigation becomes negative.25                                                              23 Saraceno (2008) provides a similar analysis that assumes inconsistent priors. 24 In the case of an unconventional solution, the payoff may differ from zero. However, for the sake of simplicity, this analysis focuses on cases where claimants give up and do not legally proceed. 25 Note that this is consistent with the literature on credible threat and settlement. See, among others, Nalebuff (1987), who investigates both the problem of credible threat and the commitment to go to court of a claimant who has a PEV suit. 10   Therefore, although parties can avoid a trial by settling the case, K wants to access the judiciary to legally resolve the dispute, but only if she has a positive prior on litigation outcome. This explains well the complementarity between litigation and settlement: the latter can be an alternative solution to the former only when litigation is feasible and represents a credible threat. In summary, K accesses justice iff her expected litigation outcome is positive, such that: . (1) When the access to justice condition (1) holds, K can make a credible proposal of settlement to the defendant. She prefers settlement only when she can bargain a settlement amount (S) greater than (or equal to) her expected litigation outcome—thus, when . Obviously, the defendant (Δ) accepts the settlement agreement only if S is smaller than (or equal to) his expected litigation outcome—thus, when: However, the claimant—who naturally wants to maximize her overall payoff—does not know the defendant’s type. Therefore, she faces the usual tradeoff between demanding a high amount that is more easily rejected, and being satisfied with a lower amount that is sure to be accepted. Two equilibrium solutions arise: a pooling strategy equilibrium, and a screening strategy equilibrium. If K demands (pooling strategy), the probability of rejection is null and the case is sure to be settled. Asking for less would be irrational for the claimant. If K demands (screening strategy), the proposal is accepted only by a type-1 defendant (liable)—therefore, with a probability p. Asking for more would be irrational, since the demand would be surely rejected. In the case of a pooling strategy, K obtains a payoff equal to S₀; otherwise, with a screening strategy, she expects to obtain . K’s optimal strategy derives from a comparison of the two possible payoffs. In particular, K opts for a screening strategy when the probability of facing a liable defendant is sufficiently high—that is, when: (2) Two relevant thresholds can be identified with respect to p. The first, the access-to-justice threshold ( ), concerns the possibility K accessing justice. The second, the trial-selection threshold— namely, —concerns the possible legal solutions (i.e. litigation, screening settlement, or pooling settlement) that can be adopted by the parties. ( )Kp c A Kp c ( )KS p c A  0 1 if = (1 ) if = S c A S c A          0S c A 1 (1 )S c A  1 - (1- ) KpS p c A (1 ) K K c c p c c       Kc   1(1 )K Kc c c c     11   In analyzing the thresholds, one must note that the former lies to the left of the latter iff . Therefore, two cases depending on the relative size of the parameters can be distinguished. Case I.  For , no access to justice  For ∆ ∆ , pooling settlement;  For ∆ ∆ , screening settlement with prob. p, litigation with prob. (1-p). Case II.     For , no access to justice  For , screening settlement with prob. p, litigation with prob. (1-p).   The two cases are illustrated in Figure 1. Cases with greater legal merit access justice more frequently than those with lower legal merit. As described in the literature, lower-merit claims accessing the judiciary are settled via pooling settlements (as in case I); those of “intermediate” merit are likely to be litigated, while those of high merit are probably settled via screening settlements. Figure 1. Dispute resolution: parameter thresholds (p). Concerning the parameter restrictions that determine the case I or case II typology, note that ∆ measures the overall litigation costs (for an amount-at-stake unit), while the ratio ∆/ can be interpreted as a measure of economic-power asymmetry between the parties. When parties are symmetric in terms of economic power (i.e., bear the same litigation costs), case I will include cases that are characterized by lower overall litigation ( ). On the other hand, when costs are relatively high ( ), disputes fall into the case II category.  K Kc c c c     12 1K K K K c c c c c c c          12 1K K K K c c c c c c c        Kc c 1 2  Kc c 1 2  12   For a given level of total litigation costs, case I corresponds to a relatively more powerful claimant who can litigate by paying a low share of the overall costs. Conversely, case II corresponds to a more powerful defendant who is able to stay in trial by paying a lower share of overall litigation costs. Figure 2 shows how the two cases are determined, for different litigation cost levels.26 Appendix A.1. further discusses how changes in the parameters shift the analysis from case I to case II, and vice versa. Figure 2. Litigation costs and analytical cases 3.2.2. Rates of access to justice, settlement, and litigation: Comparative statics The analysis below illustrates how changes in the relevant parameters affect litigation and access to justice for an overall unitary amount of disputes emerging within a society. The following exercise in comparative statics is carried out while assuming that each claimant–defendant pair has a dispute characterized by a certain legal merit p i.i.d. as a standard uniform distribution: 27 We define a number of measures that are relevant to policy implications:  J is the rate of access to justice. This is a measure of demand for legal remedies. Its complement to 1 measures the rate of disputes remaining unresolved (or unconventionally resolved).  l, s0, and s1 are the absolute rates of litigation, pooling settlement, and screening settlement, respectively. They naturally sum to J. As seen previously, two cases must be distinguished in line with the parameter restrictions. Table 1 provides the absolute rates for the two cases. All rates can be easily rewritten as a function of A. In addition, since the literature usually analyzes litigation and settlement rates by focusing on claims in the shadow of the court—namely, those that can actually access the judiciary—we define:  l/J and s/J as the standardized rates of litigation and settlement, respectively. They naturally sum to 1. Standardized rates can be calculated simply by dividing the corresponding absolute rates by J.                                                              26 The red curve corresponding to equation represents the frontier along which the two thresholds overlap perfectly. Along the 45-degree line, the costs are symmetric. 27 The use of the uniform distribution allows us to obtain very tractable results. For other symmetric probability distributions of p, the uniform distribution provides robust insights. Asymmetric distributions complicate the analysis without substantially jeopardizing general results.  0,1 .p u   12 1K Kc c c    13   Table 1. Absolute rates of access to justice, settlement, and litigation Case I.  Case II.  Tables 2 and 3 summarize the signs of the partial derivatives of the rates with respect to the model parameters. Uncertain signs are discussed in the text, as their analysis offers useful insights. Details are provided in Appendix A.2. Results of the comparative statics both support a number of Propositions (1– 4) and allow us to discuss a number of policies. Case I Regarding access to justice, it is easy to understand that access to justice positively depends on the amount at stake, while depending negatively on the claimant’s litigation costs. Given the allocation of litigation costs, the defendant costs do not influence access to justice. Comparative statics on the defendant’s litigation costs provides standard and intuitive results: high costs discourage (screening) settlement against litigation, in both absolute and standardized terms. Table 2. Case I: Effects of parameter changes on absolute and standardized rates A J - 0 + s0 - + - if s1 - - + s - + - if l - - + s /J + if + - if l /J - if - + if is the elasticity of J with respect to . Analysis of the claimant costs and the amount at stake shows less-than-standard but fairly sound insights. Increasing the claimant costs reduces both settlement (pooling and screening) and litigation   12 1K Kc c c      12 1K Kc c c            1 1 0 1 1 2 1 0 1 2 1 2 1 1 1 1 2 1 1 1 2 1 1 1 2 1 K K K K K K K K Kc c c Kc c Kc K K c c K c c K K K c c c c K J dp c c c s dp c c c c c s pdp c c c s s s c c c l p dp c c                                                           1 0 1 2 1 1 2 1 0 1 1 2 1 1 1 2 K K K Kc Kc Kc J dp c s s s pdp c l p dp c                Kc c  , 1 KJ c K c     , 1 KJ c K c     , 1 KJ c K c     , 1 KJ c     , 1 KJ c K c     , 1 KJ c    , K K J c K cJ c J     Kc 14   because then fewer claims can access justice. Increasing the amount at stake unambiguously increases both screening settlement and litigation; in fact, in such cases, more claims can access justice, and those characterized by a higher probability of success are settled for a screening amount. Litigation increases through two drivers: augmented access to justice, and a partial shift of some claims from pooling settlement to litigation. The remaining effects are ambiguous. Only under some parameter restrictions are the effects as expected. To discuss these restrictions, we also resort to the (absolute value of the) elasticity of the demand for legal remedies . This is a monotonically increasing function of , defined over the interval . Concerning the effects of changes in on the standardized rate of litigation (settlement), it is evident that increasing the claimant cost reduces both the proportion of disputes that go to trial and the proportion of disputes that can access justice. This combined action can increase or decrease the standardized rate of litigation (settlement). The standardized rates of litigation and settlement behave as usual—namely, the former decreases, while the latter increases by the same amount in —only when corresponding to , 1 ˆ( ) ( ) 1, , 2K J c K K c c c c c c            (details in Appendix A.2). Figure 3 (left) illustrates the parameter restriction in terms of costs. The dashed dark line in the graph represents the elasticity , ( )KJ c Kc , which can be measured along the y-axis. Figure 3. Effects of changes in on the standardized rates of litigation and settlement: Case I Figure 3 (right) shows the parameter restriction in terms of elasticity. In particular, the increasing curve represents the elasticity of the demand for legal remedies, along the frontier between case I and   1, 1K K J c K K K cJ c c c J       Kc  0,  Kc Kc 1 3c c   Kc 15   case II; it is also the upper limit of the elasticity for case I.28 The decreasing curve corresponds to the threshold ˆ( )c  , which is always (significantly) smaller than 1. The standardized rate of litigation (settlement) decreases (increases) with an increase in the claimant’s litigation cost, as usually described in the literature—but only if the demand for legal remedies is sufficiently inelastic (light-grey areas in both figures). It is evident that when , ( ) 1KJ c Kc  , the effect of reduced access to justice prevails, and the standardized rate of litigation increases (settlement decreases). Increasing the amount at stake ambiguously affects both the absolute rate of pooling settlement and the absolute rate of total settlement. In fact, a higher amount at stake both favors access to justice and shifts some claims from pooling to screening settlement and litigation. This happens because the claimant is asking for more to settle. On the other hand, a larger amount at stake spurs the defendant to settle. The combined effects can increase or decrease the absolute rates of pooling and total settlement. The absolute rate of pooling settlement decreases in A under the following parameter restriction: . The parameter restriction to have an absolute rate of settlement decreasing in A is stricter: . Analysis of these restrictions is not straightforward; details are discussed in Appendix A.2. These parameter restrictions on parties’ costs correspond to the elasticity threshold ˆ̂( ) 1 ,Kc c c    ; this implies that an increase in the amount at stake reduces the rate of pooling settlement only when a claimant’s litigation cost is sufficiently low—or, in other words, when the demand for legal remedies is inelastic. Therefore, when the demand is elastic (or there is unitary elasticity), an increase in the amount at stake enlarges the rate of pooling settlement. Note that the second parameter restriction is more binding than the first one; we can conclude that, when the demand for legal remedies is elastic (or there is unitary elasticity), the absolute rate of settlement is increasing in A. The intuition is clear: when the demand for legal remedies is elastic, the effect of augmented access to justice owing to a greater amount at stake prevails on the partial shifting from settlement to litigation. Concerning the standardized rate of litigation, note that a higher amount at stake enlarges both the proportion of disputes that go in trial and the proportion of disputes that access justice. This combined action can increase or decrease the standardized rate of litigation. The latter increases in only when . In terms of elasticity, this restriction corresponds to  2, 1 18 9 1 1 ( ) 1 2 4K J c c c c c c                (details in Appendix A.2.). Figure 4 (left) illustrates the parameter restriction in terms of costs. As usual, the dashed dark line in the graph                                                              28 Elasticity along the frontier has the equation . 2 K K Kc <(c +c )(1+c +c )    3 K K Kc <(c +c )(1+c +c )    A      1> 3 1 1- 3 1K K Kc c c c       0.5 0.5 4c c c      16   represents , ( )KJ c Kc , which can be measured along the y-axis. Figure 4 (right) shows the parameter restriction in terms of elasticity. Figure 4. Effects of changes in on the standardized rates of litigation and settlement: Case I The thinner line corresponds to the threshold . The standardized rate of litigation (settlement) is increasing (decreasing) in the amount at stake, only if the elasticity of the demand for legal remedies is sufficiently low (light grey areas in both figures). In particular, for case I, when , ( ) 1KJ c Kc  , then , ( ) ( ), ,KJ c K Kc c c c     . Therefore, when the demand for legal remedies is inelastic, the standardized rate of litigation (settlement) is increasing (decreasing) in A. When the elasticity is high and the defendant cost is sufficiently large (therefore, for values that are close to the frontier and between case I and case II), the standardized rate of settlement can be decreasing in A. The insight is intuitive: when the defendant incurs a high cost to stay in trial, he has a strong incentive to settle. Therefore, the augmented access to justice stemming from a higher amount at stake results in more settlement and less litigation. Case II Analysis concerning case II is simpler, since the effects of parameter changes on the relevant rates are unambiguous. As usual, low claimant costs and a high amount at stake increase access to justice. Table 3. Effects of parameter changes on absolute and standardized rates: Case II A J - 0 + s=s1 - 0 + l - 0 + s /J + 0 - l /J - 0 + A  Kc c 17   Nonetheless, even in this case, some of the current results depart from those in the standard literature. In particular, it is evident that defendant costs do not affect both absolute and standardized rates. Conversely, as in the standard literature, higher claimant costs and a lower amount at stake favor settlement against litigation for claims in the shadow of the court (standardized rates). On the other hand, higher claimant costs and a lower amount at stake discourage both settlement and litigation. 3.2.3. Propositions and remarks Given the results of the analysis in the previous subsection, it is possible to summarize the most relevant results through a number of propositions. Proposition 1. Claims characterized by a higher legal merit can access the judiciary more easily. The rate of access to justice is decreasing in the claimant cost and increasing in the amount at stake. It is not influenced by the defendant cost. Proposition 2. The absolute rate of litigation is decreasing in the claimant cost, increasing in the amount at stake, and negatively or not at all affected by the defendant cost (case I and case II, respectively). Propositions 1 and 2 illustrate the potential tradeoff between favoring access to justice and discouraging litigation through the enactment of policies, resulting in larger litigation costs among claimants. Furthermore, even if able to encourage access to justice, procedures that inflate the amount at stake of lawsuits must be carefully appraised, since they ultimately promote litigation. However, the aforementioned propositions also show that the tradeoff does not necessarily emerge. In particular, and different from the standard literature, the model used herein shows that the parties’ costs asymmetrically affect dispute selection for trial. First, higher defendant costs do not discourage access to justice, even as they potentially curtail litigation. In particular, larger defendant costs will reduce the litigation rate, provided the defendant is “sufficiently exposed” to the costs of going to trial (case I). On the other hand, when the defendant bears litigation costs that are low relative to the overall litigation costs (case II), marginal enlargements in his costs will not affect the litigation rates, since the rate of access to justice will remain the same and the selection of claims between (screening) settlement and trial will be driven only by the probability of claimant success. Proposition 3. Given (case I), the standardized rate of litigation (settlement) is decreasing (increasing) in the claimant cost and increasing (decreasing) in the amount at stake, only if the demand for legal remedies is sufficiently inelastic. The standardized rate of litigation (settlement) is always decreasing (increasing) in the defendant cost.   12 1K Kc c c    18   Given   (case II), the standardized rate of litigation (settlement) is decreasing in the claimant cost, increasing in the amount at stake, and not affected by the defendant cost. Proposition 3 shows that reductions in litigation costs and/or increases in the amount at stake do not necessarily promote the standardized rate of litigation. These results—which extend beyond those usually seen in the standard literature—are driven by the fact that here we take into account both litigation and access to justice. In particular, case I illustrates that the elasticity of the demand for legal remedies plays a key role in determining the effects of changes in parties’ costs and the benefit of trial on the standardized rate of litigation (settlement). Finally, policymakers with an interest in addressing the double issue of favoring access to justice while discouraging litigation should put additional effort into investigating the elasticity of the demand for legal remedies in different systems and for different legal matters. 3.3. Revising the social problem Given the model of the parties’ behavior presented in the previous subsection, we return to the social problem. Recalling that the overall amount of disputes emerging within society is standardized to 1, the representative dispute is assumed to be characterized as that between Δ and K. Note that parties’ private litigation costs are transfers (in favor of their lawyers, to pay litigation fees, etc.), but that from a social perspective, the average net externality stemming from the resolution of a dispute by litigation is λ. If the dispute is not legally resolved, society bears a net negative externality γ. Now, the social loss function (1) needs to be rewritten as: (3) It is straightforward that, for a given rate of access to justice, policies that are able to reduce the absolute litigation rate can unambiguously moderate the social costs of dispute resolution. More caution is required with policies that affect both rates. 3.3.1. Socially meritorious claims Recalling that and distinguishing between cases I and II, (3) can be rewritten as: .   12 1K Kc c c     1 Jl     1 KJ c        2 2 1 in Case I 1 in 1 2 2 Case I 1 I 2 J c J J J                19   In both cases, the first term of the sum represents the social cost of dispute resolution owing to litigation, while the second term is the social cost owing to the lack of legal resolution for justiciable problems. Since the first term is increasing in J and the second one is decreasing, favoring access to justice involves a tradeoff because of the increase in litigation. A simple condition is necessary (and sufficient) to having the social costs of dispute resolution decrease in J for both cases (see Appendix A.3.): (4) This condition provides some insights that are valuable from a policy perspective. First, when the social cost stemming from a lack of legal remedies is greater than or even equal to that borne by society for litigation, improving access to justice moderates the social costs of dispute resolution (note that is always smaller than 1). The intuition is simple: since not every justiciable problem shifted from the sample of those unresolved to the sample of those accessing the judiciary is resolved through litigation, improving access to justice unambiguously reduces the social cost of dispute resolution. Thanks to settlement, this is true even when the social cost stemming from a lack of legal remedies is equal to the social cost of litigation. Condition (4) also suggests that, in the debate on the concept of meritorious claims, it would be useful to distinguish between socially meritorious claims and privately meritorious claims. Socially meritorious claims can be identified as those disputes that are characterized by the claimants’ marginal propensity to litigate being smaller than the social opportunity-cost of access to justice ( ). Privately meritorious claims continue to be identifiable as those characterized by a PEV ( ). Naturally, the two concepts do not necessarily overlap. 3.3.2. Propositions and policy analysis Given the aforementioned analysis, it is possible to summarize the most relevant results of the model with respect to the social perspective, through a number of propositions and policy remarks. Proposition 4. Discouraging litigation without affecting access to justice is socially efficient. Note that this statement specifically concerns PEV lawsuits that are in the shadow of the court, since they can be actually litigated in the event of settlement failure. Proposition 5. Favoring access to justice always increases litigation; this can result in ambiguous social effects. It is always efficient to improve access to justice for socially meritorious claims, which are defined as those claims characterized by the claimant’s marginal propensity to litigate being 0 iff K l J c         Kl c     Kp c 20   smaller than the social opportunity-cost of access to justice. At least, this implies that it is always efficient to improve access to justice when the social cost stemming from a lack of legal remedies is greater than or even equal to the cost of litigation.   By combining the results of this subsection with those derived in the previous one, one can draw some policy implications. In particular, making litigation expensive for parties by charging claimants high litigation fees ambiguously affects the social cost of dispute resolution. Since this kind of policy discourages both litigation and access to justice, it exacerbates the tradeoff between the two policy goals. This sort of intervention could be useful only in a context of legal matters that involve very low social costs owing to a lack of resolutions and relatively high litigation costs. Conversely, higher litigation fees charged to defendants may reduce the expected social cost of dispute resolution by discouraging litigation, but while not affecting access to justice. However, this policy would also come with some limitations. The first limitation is of procedural fairness: it could be unfair to impose particularly high litigation costs on a defendant, who has in fact been forced into the process of defending him or herself. Discussions of fairness, however, extend beyond the present analysis. The second limitation stems from the fact that making litigation more expensive for defendants is ineffective when a pooling settlement is not feasible (case II). On the other hand, significant increases in defendant costs can make a pooling settlement feasible, finally resulting in less litigation. (On the shift from case II to case I, see Appendix A.1.) Concerning policies that affect the amount at stake, we mention only punitive damages and forms of civil or additional penalties. Punitive damages are paid by the defendant in favor of the winning claimant, with the aim of acting as a deterrent. They can be seen as an increase in A (perhaps they are also able to reduce γ). Punitive damages ambiguously affect the expected social costs of dispute resolution, given the usual tradeoff between the augmented rate of access to justice and the rising absolute rate of litigation. From a social perspective, such policies should be implemented only for socially meritorious claims. Penalties that are paid to the state—like civil or additional penalties—typically increase the amount at stake only for the defendant, without affecting the claimant’s amount at stake. They can be seen as an additional litigation cost paid by the defendant, but only in the case of the claimant’s success. They can discourage litigation without influencing access to justice. In addition, they might also be beneficial in terms of improved deterrence, perhaps reducing γ. 3.4. Claimants under budget constraints The above analysis completely ignores the possibility that the parties cannot pay their litigation costs. Since this study focuses on access-to-justice issues, the analysis below introduces a budget constraint for the claimant. On the other hand, the defendant continues to be assumed always solvent 21   (e.g., a large and professional defendant, or someone covered by insurance), and we choose not to consider “judgment proof” problems.29 Define ∈(0,∞) as K’s wealth normalized by A. In such a case, condition (1) is not enough to guarantee access to justice. An additional condition must be verified: the claimant’s wealth must be sufficient to cover the litigation cost ( ). No information asymmetry exists between the parties concerning their wealth.30 In summary, under the claimant’s budget constraint, the condition to access justice is: (5) Assume that normalized wealth among the population of potential claimants is a random variable distributed according to the density function h, with cumulative function H and independent of p. Note that the probability that the claimant is able to cover her litigation costs is , which is monotonically decreasing in and, recalling that , monotonically increasing in A. The rate of access to justice under a budget constraint— —is always smaller than that lacking a budget constraint. It is trivial to note that for a given probability of success, an unconstrained population of claimants can more readily access justice than a constrained one. Additionally, the absolute rate of litigation under a budget constraint— in case I and in case II—is always smaller than that without a budget constraint. On the other hand, the standardized rates of litigation (settlement) with or without a budget constraint are the same. These findings can be summarized by the following proposition. Proposition 6. The standardized rate of litigation (settlement) is not affected by the fact that the access to justice of some claimants is hampered by their budget constraints. Conversely, both the absolute rate of litigation and the rate of access to justice are smaller when there is a budget constraint for claimants.                                                              29 A judgment proof problem occurs when a defendant does not pay the appropriate damage award—for instance, because he or she goes bankrupt. See, for instance, Shavell (1986) and Summer (1983). 30 The capacity of the claimant to pay for litigation costs is obviously a further element that plays a role in the credibility of the threat to go to trial. Relaxing the hypothesis that the defendant knows the wealth of the claimant complicates the dynamics of settlement bargaining, without adding any insight useful to the aims of this study. Moreover, it seems sound to assume that the defendant can infer or even know the claimant’s wealth since in the real world, for instance, relations between parties are mediated by legal firms and lawyers that work as (costly) signals of claimant wealth. w Kw c K K p c w c    Pr( ) 1 ( )K Kw c H c   Kc K Kc C A     1 1K Kc H c      212 1 1K Kc c H c          212 1 1 K K c H c   22   Again, analysis of the absolute rates highlights the potential tradeoff between litigation and access to justice: less-stringent budget constraints result in more access to justice, but also in more litigation. On the other hand, since we consider exogenous litigation costs, once in the shadow of the court, “poorer” claimants are no different from “richer” ones, in terms of litigation rate. 3.5. Social tradeoff and legal aid Given the model of the parties’ behavior with budget constraints, the social loss function becomes: . (6) The social cost of dispute resolution when claimants’ behavior is restricted by budget constraints (6) is not necessarily larger than that lacking budget constraints (3). Actually, under budget constraints, there is less litigation—but also, fewer disputes are legally resolved. However, in comparing (3) and (6), it is easy to see that if (6.1.). This condition bears several implications. First, since the standardized rate of litigation is always smaller than 1, when the social cost stemming from a lack of legal remedies is greater than or even equal to the social cost of litigation, the inability of a part of the population to access the judiciary (owing to budget constraints) relates not only to a fairness problem but also to a degradation of social conditions because the social costs of dispute resolution are higher. This suggests that reforms and policies that aim to improve access to justice should focus on legal matters that when unresolved relate to high social costs (i.e., family law matters). From this perspective, legal aid as a form of litigation subsidization is an important issue. Legal aid is the main policy tool to arise in discussions concerning the issue of access to justice. Legal aid—as the provision of assistance to people who are otherwise unable to afford legal representation and access the court system—is specifically regulated in each country, and can differ widely in terms of coverage, amounts, and delivery models. Here, legal aid is assumed to take the form of a state fund that covers litigation costs for claimants who would otherwise be unable to access the judiciary. We choose not to consider potential abuses or moral hazard (i.e., legal aid does not determine any enrichment for recipients). In the case of a claimant’s success in trial, the legal aid amount is returned to the state. Thus, legal aid allows all claimants with insufficient wealth to proceed with their PEV claims. According to the above analysis, since we assume that legal aid is simply a transfer from the state to “poor” claimants, subsidizing litigation is socially efficient as long as the social opportunity-cost of access to justice is greater than the standardized rate of litigation. In particular, we can verify that it is socially efficient in subsidizing both all the socially meritorious claims falling into the case II category, and those included in case I that are characterized by a sufficiently inelastic demand for legal remedies ( ).      . . 1 ( ) 1 1 ( ) ( ) b c K K K H c J H cl H c          . .b c    l J    , KJ c   23   It can remain efficient in subsidizing socially meritorious claims that fall into the case I category, inasmuch as they are characterized by a higher elasticity of demand for legal remedies ( and as long as the standardized rate of litigation remains smaller than the social opportunity-cost of access to justice. (Proofs are provided in Appendix A.4.) Usually, however, legal aid is not a simple transfer; it is also costly for taxpayers. Below, the assumption of legal aid being a pure transfer is relaxed by assuming that legal aid is a net negative externality for taxpayers. The overall cost of legal aid for society is , since the cost of legal aid is equal to the claimant’s litigation cost, weighted by the probability of being “poor” and “losing in trial.” Therefore, the social cost of dispute resolution by using legal aid becomes: (7) It is straightforward to verify that for (7.1.). Condition (7.1.) is obviously stricter than condition (6.1.). Intuitively, when legal aid is socially costly, subsidizing litigation is efficient under a condition that is stricter than when legal aid is a simple transfer. However, condition (7.1.) can be easily interpreted, and it provides further insights. For a given standardized rate of litigation (which is always smaller than 1), it is efficient to remove financial obstacles to access to justice by providing socially costly legal aid, as long as the standardized rate of litigation remains smaller than the overall opportunity cost of access to justice (defined as the ratio of γ to the sum of both social and private litigation costs per dispute). Note that the left term of the inequality (7.1.) is increasing in p and decreasing in . Since claims that are characterized by a higher p both access justice more frequently and are litigated less frequently, condition (7.1.) is more easily satisfied for high-merit legal claims. A comparison of (6.1.) and (7.1.) shows that room for the socially efficient subsidization of litigation is reduced when legal aid is socially costly. However, improving access to justice through partial subsidization continues to be a suitable policy, especially if legal aid systems are able to select claims in terms of legal merit. This suggests that a suitable criterion by which to select the claims to be subsidized should work as a sort of legal-merit filter. Concerning litigation costs, note that lower costs do not necessarily satisfy (7.1.) easily, since the standardized rate of litigation can be either increasing or decreasing in (see subsection 3.2.). Therefore, once again, policies that affect claimant costs should be carefully evaluated. The following proposition summarizes the main insights of this subsection.  , )KJ c  ( ) (1- )K KH c l p c = ( ) (1- ) (1- )aid K Kl H c l p c J    . . >b c aid  >(1- ) K l p c J    Kc Kc 24   Proposition 7. When legal aid is a transfer, it is socially efficient in subsidizing socially meritorious claims that fall into case II, or those falling into case I that are characterized by a sufficiently inelastic demand for legal remedies. Socially meritorious claims falling into case I but characterized by a high elasticity of demand for legal remedies must be subsidized as long as the standardized rate of litigation is sufficiently low. When legal aid is a net externality for society, efficient subsidization is lower, but still positive. In general, it is socially efficient to subsidize litigation, as long as the standardized rate of litigation is lower than the social opportunity-costs of access to justice. Proposition 7 and the analysis provided in subsection 3.2. together suggest that some policies may be socially effective at best, and seriously detrimental at worst. For instance, for claims characterized by a very inelastic demand for legal remedies (i.e., falling into case I, with ), legal aid and increasing litigation costs for claimants represent a policy mix with serious adverse effects, as it would become more difficult to satisfy condition 7.1. Another possible example concerns claims that fall into case I: legal aid could be socially beneficial when defendants’ litigation costs are particularly high, since the right term of condition (7.1.) is decreasing in , even as the left term remains unaffected. Finally, any assessment of policies that influence the judiciary should be based on a careful appraisal of both their effects on the social opportunity-cost of access to justice and their influence on private parties’ behavior. Several policies determine the nature of complex interactions between litigation and access to justice; these interactions deserve particular attention, if unexpected and adverse social results are to be precluded. 4. Conclusions The dynamics of settlement and litigation in the shadow of the court have been discussed extensively by law and economics scholars. Although it is beneficial in terms of deterrence and reducing legal uncertainty by defining legal precedent, litigation is usually perceived as socially wasteful. This is certainly true if the alternative to litigation is another legal solution like settlement. However, if the alternative to litigation is that claimants fail to find any legal remedy to their justiciable problems—or even try to resolve their conflicts by unconventional means—then litigation may represent for society a suitable second-best option. This study investigates the social tradeoff that emerges between litigation and access to justice. While considering access to justice, the results of the current model lead one to question some of the standard insights of the law and economics literature on litigation and settlement rates. In particular, the results indicate that high litigation costs on the part of the claimant discourage both settlement and litigation, that high values at stake ambiguously affect settlement, and that defendant costs possibly have no role in determining the type of legal solution selected by parties. Finally, the effects of changes , KJ c    c 25   in costs and amounts at stake on the rates of settlement and litigation for claims in the shadow of the court depend upon the elasticity of the demand for legal remedies. The framework that derives from the model helps to clarify the effects of a number of policies, in terms of both litigation and access to justice. Policies that affect claimant behavior—such as those pertaining to litigation fees and punitive damages—often exacerbate the social tradeoff between litigation and access to justice. Policies that increase defendant costs—like high defense fees or additional penalties—can either reduce litigation without hampering access to justice, or be completely ineffective. Although improving access to justice will necessarily promote litigation, favoring full and effective access to the judiciary can be socially efficient. On this basis, the current study suggests the use of a new criterion by which to define and filter claims as socially meritorious. Socially meritorious claims are those where a claimant’s marginal propensity to litigate is smaller than the social opportunity-cost of access to justice. Guaranteeing access to justice of socially meritorious claims, even at the cost of promoting litigation, is always efficient. The current study also analyzed the social tradeoff between litigation and access to justice when claimants are hampered in their access to the judiciary because of budget constraints. Both the absolute rate of litigation and the rate of access to justice are smaller when some claimants are limited by their under budget constraints. From a social perspective, it is efficient to remove budget constraints by subsidizing litigation, as long as the standardized rate of litigation is lower than the social opportunity- costs of access to justice. In conclusion, although the model presented in this study simplifies assumptions within a setting that involves standard take-it-or-leave-it screening settlement bargaining, it provides a rather general framework. According to this framework, policymakers with an interest in reducing the social costs of dispute resolution should acquire a profound understanding of how policies influence both the rate of access to justice and the absolute and standardized rates of litigation. The same solution could be socially helpful in certain kinds of claims while being socially detrimental in other kinds of cases. In particular, the social opportunity-cost of access to justice, the claimants’ marginal propensity to litigate, and the elasticity of the demand for legal remedies become factors that allow us to determine the success or failure of a given policy.    26   References Acemoglu, D. and S. Johnson (2005). Unbundling institutions. 113, Journal of Political Economy, 949. AM. BAR ASS’N (1994), Legal Needs and Civil Justice: A Survey of Americans, Major Findings from the Comprehensive Legal Needs Study. www.abanet.org/legalservices/downloads/sclaid/legalneedstudy.pdf. Alcock P.C. (1976). Legal Aid: Whose Problem? 3, British Journal of Law and Society, 151-178. Bar-Gill, O. (2005). The Evolution and Persistence of Optimism in Litigation. 22, Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization 490-507. Bebchuk, L.A. (1984). Litigation and Settlement under Imperfect Information. 15, RAND Journal of Economics, 404- 415. (1988). Suing Solely to Extract a Settlement Offer. 17, Journal of Legal Studies, 437-450. (1996). A New Theory Concerning the Credibility of Success of Threats to Sue. 25, Journal of Legal Studies, 1-26. Bebchuk, L.A. and H.F. Chang. (1996) An Analysis of Fee Shifting Based on the Margin of Victory: On Frivolous Suits, Meritorious Suits, and the Role of Rule 11. 25 Journal of Legal Studies, 371-404. Boyd, C.L. and D.A. Hoffman. (2012). Litigating Toward Settlement. 3, Journal of Law, Economics, & Organization, 2-52. Buchko, K.A., Rekosh, E., and V. Terziev. (2002). “Access to Justice: Legal Aid for the Underrepresented” In Buchko, K.A., Rekosh, E., and V. Terzieva, (Eds.) Pursuing the Public Interest: A Handbook for Legal Professionals and Activists. New York: Columbia Law School. Buck, A., Day, L., Collard, S., Smith, M., and A. Patel. (2009). Outreach advice for debt problems: Research and evaluation of outreach services for financially excluded people. Legal Services Commission. Cappelletti, M., Garth, B., Weisner, J., and K.F. Koch. (1979). Access to Justice. HeinOnline. CEPEJ. (2012). European Judicial Systems. CEPEJ’s Studies No. 18. Council of Europe Publishing. CFCJ. (2012). The Cost of Justice. Weighing the Costs of fair and Effective Resolution to Legal Problems. The Canadian Forum on Civil Justice. Che, Y.K. and J. G. YI. (1993). The Role of Precedents in Repeated Litigation. 9, Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 399-424. Chung, T.Y, (1996). Settlement of Litigation under Rule 68: An Economic Analysis. 25, Journal of Legal Studies, 261-286. Cooter, R.D., Marks, S., and R. Mookin. (1982). Bargaining in the Shadow of the Law: A Testable Model of Strategic Behavior. 11, Journal of Legal Studies, 225-251. Cooter, R.D. and D.L. Rubinfeld. (1989). Economic Analysis of Legal Disputes and Their Resolution. XVII, Journal of Economics Literature, 1067-1097. (1994). An Economic Model of Legal Discovery. 23, Journal of Legal Studies, 435-463. Coumarelos, C., Wei, Z. and A.Z. Zhou. (2006). Justice made to measure: NSW legal needs survey in disadvantaged areas. Access to justice and legal needs, vol. 3, Law and Justice Foundation of NSW, Sydney. Currie, A. (2006). A national survey of the civil justice problems of low and moderate income Canadians: Incidence and patterns. 13, International Journal of the Legal Profession, 217-242. (2009a). The legal problems of everyday life. In R.L. Sandefur (Ed.), Sociology of Crime, Law and Deviance, Vol. 12, 1-41. Bingley, UK: Emerald. 27   (2009b). A lightning rod for discontent: Justiciable problems and attitudes towards the law and the justice system. In A. Buck, P. Pleasence, and N.J. Balmer (Eds.), Reaching further: Innovation, access and quality in legal services, 100-114. Legal Services Research Centre. UK: The Stationery Office. Dari-Mattiacci, G. and B. Deffains. (2007). Uncertainty of Law and the Legal Process. 163, Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 627-656. Daughety, A.F. and J.F. Reinganum. (1993). Endogenous Sequencing in Models of Settlement and Litigation. 9, Journal of Law, Economics and Organization; 314-48. (1994). Settlement Negotiations with Two Sided Asymmetric Information: Model Duality, Information Distribution, and Efficiency. 14, International Review of Law and Economics, 283-98 (2012). “Settlement” in C.W. Sanchirico (Ed.) Procedural Law and Economics, Vol. 8 Ch. 15, The Encyclopedia of Law and Economics (Second Ed.), Edward Elgar Publishing Ltd. Deffains, B. and C. Desrieux. (2011).Financing Litigation: A Comparative Analysis,” Working Paper, University of Paris II. Eisenberg, T. (1990). Testing the Selection Effect: A New Theoretical Framework with Empirical Tests. 19, Journal of Legal Studies, 337-358. Ellickson, R.C. (1991) Order without law: How neighbours settle disputes. Harvard Univ. Press Farber, H.S. and M.J. White. (1991). Medical malpractice: An Empirical Examination of the Litigation Process. 22, RAND Journal of Economics, 199-217. Fenn, P. and N. Rickman. (2010) The empirical analysis of litigation funding. In M. Tuill and L. Visscher (Eds.) New Trends in Financing Civil Litigation in Europe: A Legal, Empirical, and Economic Analysis. 131-148. Edward Elgar Publishing. Fennell M.A. Using State Legal Needs Studies to Increase Access to Justice for Low-Income Families. 48, Family Court Review, 619-630. Fournier, G.M. and T.W. Zuehlke. (1996). The Timing of Out-of-Court Settlements. 27, RAND Journal of Economics, 310-321. FRA (2011). Access to justice in Europe: An overview of challenges and opportunities European. Union Agency for Fundamental Rights, Publications Office of the European Union. Friedman, B. (2006). Taking law seriously. 4, Perspectives on Politics, 261-276. Friedman, D. and D. Wittman. (2006). Litigation with Symmetric Bargaining and Two-Sided Incomplete Information. 23, Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 98-126. Galanter, M. (1983). The Radiating Effects of Courts. 117, Empirical theories about courts, 117-142. (2010) Access to Justice in a World of Expanding Social Capability. 37, Fordham Urban Law Journal, 115-128. Garber, S. (2010). Alternative Litigation Financing in the United States. RAND Institute for Civil - Justice Law, Finance, and Capital Markets Program, Occasional Paper, 2010 Garoupa, N. (2013). Globalization and Deregulation of Legal Services. Mimeo. Garoupa, N., and F.H. Stephen. (2004). Optimal Law Enforcement with Legal Aid. 71, Economica 493- 500. Genn, H. (1999). Paths to justice: What people think about going to law. Oxford: Hart Publishing. Genn, H. and A. Paterson. (2001). Paths to justice Scotland: What people in Scotland do and think about going to law. Portland, OR: Hart Publishing. Gertner, R.H. and G.P. Miller. (1995). Settlement Escrows. 24, Journal of Legal Studies, 87-122. 28   Glaeser, E., Scheinkman, J. and A. Shleifer. (2003) The injustice of inequality. 50, Journal Monetary Economics, 199-222. Gould, J.P. (1973). The Economics of Legal Conflicts. 2, Journal of Legal Studies, 279-300. Gross, S.R. and K.D. Syverud. (1991). Getting to No: A study of Settlement Negotiations and the Selection of Cases for Trial. 90 Michigan Law Review, .319-393. Hadfield G.K. (2000) The Price of Law: How the Market for Lawyers Distorts the Justice System. 98, Michigan Law Review, 953-1006. (2008). The levers of legal design: Institutional determinants of the quality of law. 36, Journal of Comparative Economics, 43–73. (2010). Higher Demand, Lower Supply? A Comparative Assessment of the Legal Resource Landscape for Ordinary Americans. 37, Fordham Urban Law Journal, 129-150. (2013). The Cost of Law: Promoting Access to Justice through the Corporate Practice of Law. Bepress. Hay, B.L. and K.E. Spier. (1998). “Settlement of Litigation” in P. Newman (Ed.), The New Palgrave Dictionary of Law and Economics, Macmillan Reference Limited, Vol. 3, 442-451. Hylton, K.N. and H. Lin. (2010). Trial Selection Theory: A Unified Model. BU School of Law Working Paper, 10-12. Hodges, C., Vogenauer, S., and M. Tulibacka. (2009). Costs and funding of civil litigation: A comparative study. Oxford Legal Research Paper Series, Paper No 55/2009. Huang, K.C., Chen, K.P., and C.C. Lin. (2010). An Empirical Investigation of Settlement and Litigation - The Case of Taiwanese Labor Disputes. 7, Journal of Empirical Legal Studies, 786–810. Katz, A. (1990). The Effect of Frivolous Lawsuits on the Settlement of Litigation. 10, International Review of Law and Economics, 3-27. Kessler, D. (1996). Institutional Causes of Delay in the Settlement of Legal Disputes, 12, Journal of Law, Economics, and Organizations, 432-460. Kritzer, H.M. (2008) To Lawyer or Not to Lawyer: Is that the Question? 5, Journal of Empirical Legal Studies, 875-906. (2010). Examining the Real Demand for Legal Services. 37, Fordham Urban Law Journal, 255- 272. Landes, W.M. (1971). An Economic Analysis of the Court. 14, Journal of Law and Economics, 61-107. LEGAL SERVS. CORP. (2005). Documenting the Justice Gap in America: The Current Unmet Civil Legal Needs of Low-Income Americans 2005.www.lsc.gov/sites/default/files/LSC/images/justicegap.pdf (2009). Documenting the Justice Gap in America: The Current Unmet Civil Legal Needs of Low- Income Americans, 2009. www.lsc.gov/JusticeGap.pdf . Marshall, T.H. (1950). Citizenship and Social Class, and Other Essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Mattei, U. (2006). Access to Justice, Costs, and Legal Aid. XVII Congress of the International Academy of Comparative Law. Utrecht, The Netherlands Molot, J.T. (2010). Litigation Finance: A Market Solution to a Procedural Problem. 99, Georgetown Law Journal, (2010), 65-115. Mnookin, R.H. Why Negotiations fail: An Explorations of Barriers to the Resolution of Conflicts. 8, Ohaio state Journal on Dispute Resolution, 235-251. Nalebuff, B. (1987). Credible Pretrial Negotiation. 18, RAND Journal of Economics, 198-210. 29   North, D.C. (1989). Institutions and economic growth: an historical introduction.9, World Develop, 1319-1332. Pleasence, P., Balmer, N. J., and A. Buck, (2006). Causes of action: Civil law and social justice (2nd ed.). London: Legal Services Commission. (2008). The health cost of civil-law problems: Further evidence of links between civil-law problems and morbidity, and the consequential use of health services. 5, Journal of Empirical Legal Studies, 351-373. Pleasence, P., Balmer, N. J., Buck, A., O’Grady, A., and H. Genn. (2004). Civil law problems and morbidity. 58, Journal of Epidemiology and Community Health, 552-557. Pleasence, P., Balmer, N.J., Buck, A., Smith, M., and A. Patel. (2007). Mounting problems: Further evidence of the social, economic and health consequences of civil justice problems. In Pleasence, P., Buck, A., and N.J. Balmer, (Eds.), Transforming lives: Law and social process, 67-92. London: Legal Services Commission. P’ng, I.(1983). Strategic Behavior in Suit, Settlement, and Trial. 14, Bell Journal of Economics, 539- 550. Posner, R.A. (1973). An Economic Approach to Legal Procedure and Judicial Administration. 2, Journal of Legal Studies, 399-458. (1998). Creating a Legal Framework for Economic Development. 13, The World Bank Research Observer, 1-11. Polinsky, A.M. and D.L. Rubinfeld. (1993) Sanctioning Frivolous Suits: An Economic Analysis. 82 Georgia Law Journal, 397-436. (1988). The Deterrent Effect of Settlement and Trial. 8, International Review of Law and Economics, 109-116. Priest, G.L. and B. Klein. (1984). “The Selection of Disputes for Litigation. 13, Journal of Legal Studies, 1-56. Ramseyer, J.M. and E.B. Rasmusen. (2010). Comparative Litigation Rates. Harvard John M. Olin Discussion Paper Series, No. 681. Ringanum, J.F. and L.L. Wilde. (1986). Settlement, Litigation, and the Allocation of Litigation Costs. 17, RAND Journal of Economics, 557-566. Rhode, D.L. (2004). Access to justice. Oxford University Press, USA. Rodak, M. (2006). It’s About Time: A Systems Thinking Analysis of the Litigation Finance Industry and its Effect on Settlement. 155, University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 503-535. Rosemberg, D. and S. Shavell. (1985). A Model in which Suits are Brought for their Nuisance Value. 5, International Review of Law and Economics, 3-13. Rubinstein, A. (1982). Perfect Equilibrium in a Bargaining Model. 50, Econometrica, 97-110. Saraceno, M. (2008) Access to Justice and Litigation Trade-Off: A Theoretical Analysis. Paolo Baffi Centre Research Paper No. 2008-29; CLEA 2008 Meetings Paper. Shavell, S. (1982). The Social versus Private Incentive to Bring a Suit in Costly Legal System. 11, Journal of Legal Studies, 333-340. (1986). The Judgment Proof Problem. 6 International Review of Law and Economics, 45-58. (1995). Alternative Disputes Resolution: An Economic Analysis. 24, Journal of Legal Studies, 1- 28. (1997). The Fundamental Divergence between the Private and the Social Motive to Use the Legal System. 26, Journal of Legal Studies, 575-616. 30   (1999). The Level of Litigation: Private versus Social Optimality of Suit and of Settlement. 19, International Review of Law and Economics, 99-115. Schlesinger, R.B. (1988). Comparative law: cases, text, materials. Foundation Press. Schwartz, W.F. and Wickelgren, A.L. (2009). Advantage Defendant: Why Sinking Litigation Costs Makes Negative Expected Value Defenses, but not Negative Expected Value Suits, Credible. 38, Journal of Legal Studies, 235-253. Schweizer, U. (1989). Litigation and Settlement under Two Sided Incomplete Information. 56, Review of Economic Studies, 163-177. Silver, C. (2001). Does civil justice cost too much? 80, Texas Law Review, 2073-2114. Sommerlad, H (2004). Some Reflections on the Relationship between Citizenship, Access to Justice, and the Reform of Legal Aid. 31, Journal Law and Society, 345-368 Spier, K.E. (1992). The Dynamics of Pretrial Negotiation. 59, Review of Economic Studies, 93-108. (2007). “Litigation” in M. Polinsky and S. Shavell, (Eds.), Handbook of Law and Economics, Elsevier, 259-342. Stratton, M., and T. Anderson. (2008). Social, economic and health problems associated with a lack of access to the courts. Edmonton: Canadian Forum on Civil Justice. Summers, J. (1983). The Case of the Disappearing Defendant: An Economic Analysis. 132 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 145-185 Trubek ,D.M., Sarat, A., Felstinert, W.L.F., Kritzert, H.M., and J.B. Grossmant. (1983). Costs of Ordinary Litigation. 31, UCLA Law Review, 72-127. UNDP. (2004). Access to Justice: Practice Note. United Nations Development Program Publications. (2010). Integrating Legal Empowerment of the Poor in UNDP’s work A Guidance Note. United Nations Development Program Publications. U.S. Deparment of Justice (2013). The Access to Justice Initiative of the U.S. Department of Justice. Access to Justice Accomplishments. Available at http://www.justice.gov/atj/accomplishments.pdf Varano, V. And A. De Luca. (2007). Access to Justice in Italy. 7, Global Jurist (Advances, art. 6). Wang, G.H., Kim, J.Y., and J.G. YI. (1994). Litigation and Pretrial Negotiation under Incomplete Information. 10, Journal of Law, Economics and Organization; 187-200. World Bank. (2006). World Development Report 2006: Equity and Development. New York: Oxford University Press Yildiz, M. (2003). Bargaining without a Common Prior - An Immediate Agreement Theorem. 71, Econometrica, 793-811. 31   Appendix A.1 Changes in the parameters can shift the analysis from case I to case II and vice versa. Note that the access-to justice threshold (hereafter, ) changes more sharply than the trial selection threshold (hereafter, ) for a given change in . For changes in , the does not change while moves. In addition, recalling that can be written as and as , changes in A move both the thresholds (both are decreasing in A). The following observations can be derived:  Significant increases in shift case I to case II. Significant decreases in shift case II to case I.  Significant decreases in shift case I to case II. Significant increases in shift case II to case I.  With respect to A, generally moves faster than . Actually, moves slower than iff , ( - setting overall costs equal to 1 this means ). This implies that significant decreases in A generally shift case I to case II.  Since case II corresponds to the parameter restriction , significant increases in A shift case II to case I ( ). Intuitively, it is possible understanding how changes in A shift the analysis from a case to the other moving on the Figure 2 from NE to SW for increases in A and from SW to NE for decreases in A. KJ c  (1 ) K K c c T c c        Kc c J  T  Kc K C A (1 ) K K c c c c      K K C C A C C      Kc Kc c c J  T  J  T  Kc c  iff 2( ) ( )²K K K T J c c c c c c A A               3 Kc c  / ( )K Kc c c c   J T A A        32   A.2 Partial derivatives of both absolute and standardized rates of access to justice, settlement and litigation are calculated with respect to the parameters of the model for cases I and II in Table A1 and A2, respectively. Table A1. Comparative statics: Case I Case I  Table A2. Comparative statics: Case II Case II        We focus on Table A1. Uncertain signs of case I are discussed below. First column. Signs of partial derivatives of the standardized rates of settlement and litigation with respect to K’s cost are uncertain . Focus on : denominator is positive and       0 2 1 3 0 1 3 1 1 <0 1 0 1 0 1 0 1 K K K K K K K K K K s c c c s c c c c c s ss c c c l c c c                                                       0 2 2 1 3 2 0 1 2 0 1 1 1 1 2 2 2 0 1 1 / / 0 K K K K K K K K K K K K K s J c c c c c c c c c c s J c c c c s J s J s J l J c c c c                                                  3 2 / 1 2 1 0 2 1 1 K K K K K l J c c c c c c c                              0 2 1 3 0 1 3 3 0 0 1 1 1 >0 1 0 1 1 0 1 1 0 1 / 0 / <0 / >0 / / 0 K K K K K K s c c c s c c c c c s ss c c c c c l c c c s J s J c c s J s J c c s J s J c c l J l J c c                                                                                            0 2 2 1 3 0 1 3 3 0 1 20 0 1 1 21 1 0 1 0 1 0 1 0 1 0 1 * * 0 * * 0 K K K K K K K K K K s c c c A A A c c c cs A A c c s s c c cs A A A A A c c c cl A A c c s J s J J s J A A A s J s J J s J A A A s J s J s J l A A A                                                                               1 2 0 / * * 0 J A l J l J J l J A A A                    1 0 / 1 > 0 2 / 1 < 0 2 0 K K K K K K l c c s J c l J c s c c                        0 0 0 / 0 s c l c s J c l J c                       2 0 1 0 1 0 2 / 1 0 2 K K K K K cs A A cl c A A s J c A A l J c A A                      / / 0 K K l J s J c c        / K l J c   33   the sign is driven by the numerator. . Recalling that and defining the absolute value of the elasticity of the “demand for justice” as , we can rewrite and then This means that the standardized rate of litigation decreases with an increase in claimant's litigation cost only if the demand for justice is sufficiently inelastic. For an elastic demand for justice, the standardized litigation rate always increases when claimants’ costs increase. Actually, increasing claimants’ costs reduce both the amount of disputes that go in trial and the amount of disputes that access justice. This combined action can increase the standardized (and observable) rate of litigation. The opposite reasoning is valid for the standardized rate of settlement. Third column. . Solving for , it becomes where . is represented on the -axes in the Figure A1 (green curve). Figure A1. Effects of changes in on the absolute rate of pooling settlement   0 for <1-3 / 0 for =1-3 0 for >1-3 K K K K c c l J c c c c c          1 KJ c  , K K J c K cJ c J       1 , ,1K KK J c J cc                    1 , 1 , 1 , 0 for < 1 2 <1 / 0 for 1 2 <1 0 for 1 2 <1 K K K J c J c K J c c c l J c c c c c                                         2 20 2 0 for < 1 0 for < 1 0 for < 1 K K K K K K K K K c c c c c s c c c c c A c c c c c                        c 1 2 0 1 2 1 2 0 for >{ ( ), ( )} 0 for { ( ), ( )} 0 for <{ ( ), ( )} K K K K K K c f c f c s c f c f c A c f c f c          2 2 1 2 1 1 ( ) (-2 (-4 1) - 2 1), ( ) - (2 (-4 1) 2 -1) 2 2 K K K K K K K K K K f c c c c f c c c c c c         1 2{ ( ), ( )} K Kc f c f c  Kc c A 34   The dashed dark line in the graph represents the elasticity of the demand for legal remedies that can be measured on the y-axis. An increase in the amount-at-stake decreases the rate of pooling settlement only when claimant’s costs are low enough (approximately smaller than 0.2)/the demand for legal remedies is sufficiently inelastic (approximately smaller than 0.3). When the demand is elastic (or with unitary elasticity), an increase in the amount-at-stake enlarges the rate of pooling settlement for every value of the defendant cost. Since , it is straightforward that the parameter restriction in terms of is more binding. To have a settlement rate decreasing in A, K’s cost/the elasticity of the demand for legal remedies has to be lower than that one to have a rate of pooling settlement decreasing in A. Therefore, an increase in the amount-at-stake reduces the rate of settlement only when claimant cost is very low/demand is strongly inelastic. Obviously, when . Finally, when the demand for legal remedies is elastic (or with unitary elasticity), an increase in the amount-at-stake enlarges the rate of settlement for every value of litigation costs. . Solving for , it becomes .   Recalling that , the parameter restriction can be written also in terms of elasticity of the demand for legal remedies: where . This means that the standardized rate of litigation increases with an increase in amount-at-stake only if the elasticity of the demand for justice is sufficiently low (not necessarily inelastic). For a sufficiently elastic demand for justice, the standardized litigation rate can be decreasing in A. The opposite reasoning is valid for the standardized rate of settlement.          3 3 3 0 for < 1 0 for < 1 0 for < 1 K K K K K K K K K c c c c c s c c c c c A c c c c c                        Kc 0 s A    0 0 s A                     0 for > 1 2 1 / 0 for = 1 2 1 0 < 1 2 1 K K K K K K K K K K K K c c c c c c l J c c c c c c A c c c c c c                        c                  1 1 1 0 for < 3 1 1- 3 1 / 0 for = 3 1 1- 3 1 0 for > 3 1 1- 3 1 K K K K K K K K K c c c c l J c c c c A c c c c                    1, ,1K KK J c J cc           , , , 0 for > 1 / 0 for 1 0 for 1 K K K J c J c J c l J A                  21 (c + 18c +9c +1+1) 1 2c +4        35   A.3. . Substituting by l and then by social cost of dispute resolution can be rewritten as for case I and for case II. Partial derivatives with respect to J are and for case I and II respectively. By replacing again in the expressions above, the conditions to have the social cost of dispute resolution decreasing in J are: and for case I and II respectively. The two conditions correspond to a unique condition equal for both cases: . A.4. Socially meritorious claims have been defined as those characterized by . It is socially efficient a complete subsidization when (6.1). For case II which is always larger than . Therefore it is always efficient subsidizing all socially meritorious claims falling in case II. For case I, is larger than for corresponding to (see A.1.). Therefore, for socially meritorious claims with elasticity of the demand for legal remedies smaller than  condition (6.1) is always verified. For claims falling in case I and characterized by elasticity equal to /larger than ,  condition (6.1) has to be satisfied in order to have efficient subsidization.  1 Jl     1Kc J     21 2 12 JJ c       2 1 1 2 JJ        32 0J c J            0J J        1 KJ c    31 Kc c J           1 Kc J        0 iff K l J c         Kl c     l J   1 K K l c c      1 2 1 Kl J c    3 1K Kl c c c           2 1 1 11 2 K K l J c c c       <1-3 Kc c  , Semantic Scholar's Logo Search Sign InCreate Free Account You are currently offline. Some features of the site may not work correctly. DOI:10.1287/mnsc.2016.2535 Corpus ID: 3631433Justice Under Uncertainty @article{Cettolin2017JusticeUU, title={Justice Under Uncertainty}, author={E. Cettolin and A. Riedl}, journal={CESifo Working Paper Series}, year={2017} } E. Cettolin, A. Riedl Published 2017 Economics, Computer Science CESifo Working Paper Series An important element for the public support of policies is their perceived justice. At the same time most policy choices have uncertain outcomes. We report the results of a first experiment investigating just allocations of resources when some recipients are exposed to uncertainty. Although, under certainty almost all uninvolved participants distribute resources equally, they exhibit remarkable heterogeneity in just allocations under uncertainty. Moreover, uninvolved participants allocate on… Expand View on SSRN cris.maastrichtuniversity.nl Save to Library Create Alert Cite Launch Research Feed Share This Paper 21 CitationsHighly Influential Citations 1 Background Citations 8 Methods Citations 2 View All 21 Citations Citation Type Citation Type All Types Cites Results Cites Methods Cites Background Has PDF Publication Type Author More Filters More Filters Filters Sort by Relevance Sort by Most Influenced Papers Sort by Citation Count Sort by Recency Giving in the face of risk E. Cettolin, A. Riedl, Giang Tran Economics, Psychology 2016 23 PDF View 3 excerpts, cites background Save Alert Research Feed Tilburg University Giving in the face of risk E. Cettolin, A. Riedl, Giang Tran 2018 PDF View 3 excerpts, cites background Save Alert Research Feed Fairness views and political preferences: evidence from a large and heterogeneous sample Daniel Muller, S. Renes Economics 2020 PDF Save Alert Research Feed Fairness views and political preferences - Evidence from a large online experiment Daniel Muller, S. Renes Political Science 2017 27 PDF View 1 excerpt, cites methods Save Alert Research Feed Fairness Views and Political Preferences - Evidence from a representative sample M. Daniel, S. Renes Economics 2019 9 PDF View 2 excerpts, cites background Save Alert Research Feed Risking Other People's Money: Experimental Evidence on the Role of Incentives and Personality Traits O. Andersson, H. Holm, J. Tyran, E. Wengström Economics 2020 6 Save Alert Research Feed Unequal Chances: Ex Ante Fairness and Individual Control Leticia Micheli, Nickolas Gagnon 2020 View 1 excerpt, cites background Save Alert Research Feed A method to elicit beliefs as most likely intervals K. H. Schlag, J. J. V. D. Weele Mathematics 2015 18 Highly Influenced PDF View 6 excerpts, cites background and methods Save Alert Research Feed The role of ignorance in the emergence of redistribution A. Gerber, A. Nicklisch, S. Voigt Economics 2019 2 Save Alert Research Feed Unequal chances: ex ante fairness and individual control Leticia Micheli, Nickolas Gagnon Economics, Medicine Scientific reports 2020 PDF Save Alert Research Feed ... 1 2 3 ... References SHOWING 1-10 OF 94 REFERENCES SORT BYRelevance Most Influenced Papers Recency What Is Fair? Experimental Evidence D. Dickinson, Jill Tiefenthaler Economics 2000 104 PDF View 1 excerpt Save Alert Research Feed Just luck: an experimental study of risk taking and fairness A. Cappelen, James Konow, Erik Ø. Sørensen, B. Tungodden Political Science, Economics 2010 290 Highly Influential PDF View 4 excerpts, references background and methods Save Alert Research Feed Which Is the Fairest One of All? A Positive Analysis of Justice Theories James Konow Economics 2003 695 View 3 excerpts, references methods and background Save Alert Research Feed Biased Judgments of Fairness in Bargaining Linda Babcock, G. Loewenstein, Samuel Issacharoff, Colin Camerer Economics 1995 544 View 1 excerpt, references background Save Alert Research Feed Self-interest and fairness: self-serving choices of justice principles Ismael Rodríguez-Lara, Luis Moreno-Garrido Economics 2012 59 View 1 excerpt, references background Save Alert Research Feed Fair Shares: Accountability and Cognitive Dissonance in Allocation Decisions James Konow Economics 2000 727 Highly Influential PDF View 5 excerpts, references background and methods Save Alert Research Feed Dictating the Risk: Experimental Evidence on Giving in Risky Environments J. M. Brock, Andreas Lange, Erkut Y. Ozbay Economics 2013 166 PDF View 3 excerpts, references background Save Alert Research Feed The Pluralism of Fairness Ideals: An Experimental Approach Alexander W. Cappelen, Astri Drange Hole, Erik Ø. Sørensen, B. Tungodden Economics 2005 586 Highly Influential PDF View 9 excerpts, references results and background Save Alert Research Feed Interindividual Differences in Opinions about Distributive Justice E. Schokkaert, B. Capéau Economics 1991 49 View 2 excerpts, references methods and background Save Alert Research Feed Strategic Choices for Redistribution and the Veil of Ignorance: Theory and Experimental Evidence A. Gerber, A. Nicklisch, S. Voigt Economics 2013 7 PDF View 3 excerpts, references background Save Alert Research Feed ... 1 2 3 4 5 ... Related Papers Abstract 21 Citations 94 References Related Papers Stay Connected With Semantic Scholar Sign Up About Semantic Scholar Semantic Scholar is a free, AI-powered research tool for scientific literature, based at the Allen Institute for AI. Learn More → Resources DatasetsSupp.aiAPIOpen Corpus Organization About UsResearchPublishing PartnersData Partners   FAQContact Proudly built by AI2 with the help of our Collaborators Terms of Service•Privacy Policy The Allen Institute for AI By clicking accept or continuing to use the site, you agree to the terms outlined in our Privacy Policy, Terms of Service, and Dataset License ACCEPT & CONTINUE work_ikhwgdtvbbhappgrljju4bdks4 ---- 08-0536_p ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE Volume 1, Number 3, 2008 © Mary Ann Liebert, Inc. DOI: 10.1089/env.2008.0536 The Value of Environmental Justice Bill E. Lawson ABSTRACT Environmental justice, at least, entails preserving the environment as a global entity, but also making those persons who feel, have felt, have been, or are victims of environmental crimes and atrocities feel as if they are part of the solution as full members of the human community and not just the environmental dump- ing ground for the well-off. 1 INTRODUCTION FOR THIS ARTICLE, we were asked to give our thoughtsas to what Environmental justice entails. As a Black American, who is also a professor and academically trained philosopher, the question of what environmental justice entails looms large. Since my area of academic ex- pertise is African American philosophy, I have spent the past 25 years looking at the manner in which racism, sex- ism, and classism impacts on the lives of not only blacks, but also the poor. I see philosophy as being interested in questions of value. Why should we value the well being of other humans? Why should we value life itself? Why should we value the environment? There are many an- swers to these questions. The fact that there are many an- swers does not mean that there is no answer. Some an- swers are clearly bad. It does not or would not take a trained philosopher to see that some of the answers are bad answers. The philosophical goal is to mark out the bad answers and to demonstrate why they are bad. Then we must mark the competing good answers and examine these answers with an eye to the past and to the future of this planet. This is very important if we want public policies that respect the histories of all environmental stakeholders involved. Examining these arguments and claims, I think is one of the roles of the philosopher in the area of environmental justice. DISCUSSION I want to start with the Environmental Protection Agency’s definition of environmental justice: Environmental Justice is the fair treatment and meaningful involvement of all people regardless of race, color, national origin, culture, education, or in- come with respect to the development, implemen- tation, and enforcement of environmental laws, reg- ulations, and policies. Fair Treatment means that no group of people, including racial, ethnic, or socioe- conomic groups, should bear a disproportionate share of the negative environmental consequences resulting from industrial, municipal, and commer- cial operations or the execution of federal, state, lo- cal, and tribal environmental programs and policies. Meaningful Involvement means that: (1) potentially affected community residents have an appropriate opportunity to participate in decisions about a pro- posed activity that will affect their environment and/or health; (2) the public’s contribution can in- fluence the regulatory agency’s decision; (3) the con- cerns of all participants involved will be considered in the decision-making process; and (4) the decision- makers seek out and facilitate the involvement of those potentially affected.1 I want to focus on item number 3 in the section Mean- ingful Involvement as my starting point for what envi- ronmental justice entails. I argue that environmental jus- tice entails, at least, preserving the environment as a global entity but also making those persons who feel, have felt, and have been victims of environmental crimes and atrocities feel as if they are part of the solution as full members of the human community and not the dumping ground for the rest of us. Dr. Lawson is professor of philosophy at the University of Memphis in Memphis Tennessee. 1 �http://www.epa.gov/compliance/resources/faqs/ej/ index.html� (2008). I will use one of the major problems facing environ- mentalists as my focal point. The problem is the bringing together of diverse environmental stakeholders to resolve issues regarding the environment. This is particularly dif- ficult when environmental policies appear to be rooted in class or race divisions. That is, where members of poor or raced groups have been the victims of environmental policies that have benefited the well-off. (Lawson, 2006) I want to focus, in this article, on environmental stake- holders of color, particularly African Americans in the United States. Not because I think that their plight is more important than that of the poor in general, but because the African American experience in the United States has been my area of study. The African American experience is unique in that their history must be situated in a state that political and so- cial policies are supposedly underpinned by liberal tenets that are meant to garner respect for worth and autonomy of each individual. It is clear that these liberal tenets were not applied to the social and political experiences of African Americans for most of their tenure in the United States. Not only have African Americans had to fight for application of the liberal tenets to their status as citizens, these same tenets have often been used against them. I have argued elsewhere how the appeal to protection of private property has been used to keep African Ameri- cans out of white communities and how laws have been enforced to ensure that white autonomy has been pro- tected and respected. The history of the environmental policies attests to the manner in which African Americans are not respected as full members of the political order. Robert Bullard and others have documented the man- ner in which neighborhoods of persons of color have been the site of environmental contamination. Not only have these communities been sites of contamination but also when it comes time to clean up the sites, the government is slow or reluctant to do so. These actions by state and federal officials have led to feelings of mistrust between these communities and the government at all levels. There is no wondering why there would be mistrust between members of communities of color and the local, state, and federal government as well as environmentalists who of- ten see the land that members of communities of color live on as not the part of the environment that has to be protected. The actions of these groups have fostered a sense of mistrust between these communities and those agencies and groups that purport to be concerned with the environment. This mistrust is especially problematic when the divisions have been race-based. Race based dis- crimination has been a long-standing problem for African Americans. Because of the history of racism, African Americans who should be anxious to join environmental coalitions are often reluctant to join with mainstream groups push- ing for global action regarding the environment. This re- luctance often leads mainstream environmentalists to ar- gue that this group is uncaring when it comes to the global environment. Thus there are various studies of the envi- ronmental concern of African Americans that tend to cor- relate their environmental concerns with local environ- mental issues. That African Americans would be inter- ested or concerned with their local space should not be surprising. After all there is the problem of NIMBY (Not In My Back Yard) that is held by persons across the racial and economic spectrum. The difference is that the back- yards of African Americans have not been respected. Gen- erally, this lack of respect has been caused by racism. This is not to claim that environmentalists are or have been racist. However, we must agree that some environ- mental policies seem to hint strongly of racist intent. Here, I only want to claim that racism has impacted on how African Americans view their status in the United States. Even environmentalists can agree that racism has been and continues to be a problem for African Americans, but also note that environmental concerns are not like racism or sexism, which may affect a particular group of people, environmental concerns impact on us all and thus should be the concern of us all. This means that as members of the human family we have a vested interest in good en- vironmental policy and a clean planet. It is thus in the best interest of all persons to be in- volved in the push to clean up and cool down the planet. If this answer does not suffice, environmentalists could argue that not only are persons of color (African Ameri- cans) often the victims of bad environmental policies, they often bear the brunt of harm done by these polices. They should be willing participants in the movement for well- formed environmental policies and acts. In addition, African Americans are to some degree responsible for the degrading of the environment. It is clear that members of these communities have an environmental footprint that impacts on the health of the planet. At this point the environmentalist would sit down thinking that he or she has adequately addressed the question of the responsibility of members of communities of color (African Americans) to join with other concerned citizens of the world to help save the environment. But notice what question the environmentalist has answered. It is with one noticeable exception the question of why should persons of color be concerned with global issues of the environment. The question I want to address is why should they feel any responsibility to participate in envi- ronmental programs. The answer that they also have an environmental footprint seems to not carry much weight or at least not as much weight as some environmentalists think it should. Why do I think that this is the case? I want to draw a distinction between being or feeling concerned and being or feeling responsible. By concern I mean caring about and giving attention to some particu- lar interest. Being responsible, on the other hand, has two related meanings: (1) being the cause of some action and (2) being expected to feel obliged to participate in some joint action. Here I want to draw on the experiences of African Americans and their environmental problems. Let me be clear: my use of the African American experience is not meant to suggest that they are the only group that will have a problem feeling responsibility to global environ- mental concerns. If it is true that African Americans feel that they are victims of racism and the resulting envi- LAWSON2 ronmental problems are a consequence of the racism, why should they feel any responsibility to help the persons re- sponsible for both their plight and the plight of the planet? One might think that to hold such a position is very short sighted. Yet, if we draw on the liberal model of the re- sponsibilities of the individual, then it become apparent that the persons responsible for the wrongdoing have the greater burden of responsibility in correcting it. I want to suggest that a part of the reason this attitude can be man- ifest is we live in a society that puts the onus of respon- sibility on individuals or groups for the wrongs they have done. That is, if you do the wrong, you are responsible for correcting it. This means for many persons of color, not only have “white folk” done evil to persons of color, they have harmed the planet. It is therefore their respon- sibility to fix it. In this manner blacks can feel concern but not responsible for the environmental problems of the planet. I am not suggesting that African Americans have no responsibility to help with environmental projects. I do contend that given the history of racist social interac- tion there are feelings that whites have more responsibil- ity for harming the planet than do persons of color. Be- cause of the racial history, there are often feelings of mistrust between African Americans and those persons that push some form of collective responsibility for the environment. Is it possible to alleviate some of the mistrust? I think that it is possible but it will require a great deal of work on the part of both parties. What I want to suggest is that those persons concerned with environmental justice re- think how they approach persons of color in regard to working on environmental issues. I am suggesting that they ask: Why should poor persons of color feel any re- sponsibility to participate in environmental programs? This question points to one of the essential values of en- vironmental justice. I contend that not only cleaning up and preserving the environment as a global entity but making those persons who feel, have felt, are, or have been victims of environ- mental crimes and atrocities feel as if they are part of the solution as full members of the human community and not the dumping ground for the wealthy of the world. These are concerns that environmental groups have to ad- dress. As I write this article a major political party has nom- inated the first African American, Barack Obama, for the president of the United States. This is a historic moment. Yet, we must be careful as to how we use his candidacy in our future moral and political deliberations. I think that this point is very important for those of us concerned with environmental issues. His candidacy will give whites a chance to show that they are not racist. Some will claim that: “I voted for Obama therefore I couldn’t be racist.” Logically the conclusion does not follow from the act of voting for Obama. We must be on our guard to remind those persons who use this claim as proof that their en- vironmental policies cannot be racist are wrong. This is an important moment in the social and political history of the United States, but we should not be lulled into ide- ological complacency because of Obama’s political as- cendency. We must remember that racism is still a prob- lem and a vote for Obama may soothe one’s conscience but it does not follow that in other areas of one’s life race does not play an important role. Those of us concerned with environmental justice should not forget this salient point. CONCLUSION In sum, the failure of the environmental movement to address the feelings of victims of bad and unjust envi- ronmental policies that have often been seen as racial atrocities may be a reason that many persons of color, in this case African Americans, feel no responsibility to join with environmentalists to address environmental issues beyond their local issues. Environmentalists want to claim that we are all in this together. We may all be in it together but some of us have been getting screwed. Now you want us to join you in a global environmental program, why should persons of color trust environmentalists. The challenge for both en- vironmentalists and environmental justice advocates is to allay the fears of persons of color that the burden for en- vironmental reclamation will not fall solely on persons of color. In the end, environmentalists must provide argu- ments that are sound and rooted in the history of all of the parties concerned. REFERENCES Lawson, Bill E. Faces of Environmental Racism, 2nd edition, eds. Laura Westra and Bill E. Lawson (Rowman and Lit- tlefield, 2001). “Living For the City: Urban United States and Environmen- tal Justice,” in Faces of Environmental Racism, eds. L. Wes- tra and P. Wenz (Rowman and Littlefield, l995) pp. 41–55. “Racist Property Holdings and Environmental Coalitions: Addressing Memories of Environmental Injustice” in Echoes from the Poisoned Well, eds. Sylvia Hood Washing- ton, Heather Goodall, and Paul Rosier (Lexington Books, 2006). Address correspondence to: Bill E. Lawson 327 Clement University of Memphis Memphis, TN 38152 E-mail: belawson@memphis.edu VALUE OF ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE 3 work_ikix5whjtjcqvjtjlaex5od6mq ---- A theory of justice? P H I L I P P E T T I T A T H E O R Y O F J U S T I C E ? * ABSTRACT. This is a critical analysis o f J o h n Rawls's A Theory o f Justice. Rawls offers a theoretical justification o f social democratic principles o f justice. H e argues that they are the principles which rational men would choose, under defined constraints, in an original position o f social contract. The author criticises Rawls's assumption that men o f any background, o f any socialisation, would choose these principles in the original position. H e argues that the choice which Rawls imputes to his contractors reflects a specific s o c i a l i s a t i o n - one dominant in Western democracies. The theory is useful because it systematises a particular sense o f justice; it is in no sense however a universal theory. My intention is to show that the contractual theory o f justice defended by John Rawls does not have the status of a universal theory (John Rawls, A Theory o f Justice, Oxford 1972 - henceforth 'J'). By a universal theory, I mean a theory which people in different circumstances, particularly people in different cultures, would have equal reason to accept - granted that they could all understand the argument for it. I intend to show that the most Rawls can claim is that his theory explicates the sense of justice of people in a particular society. The paper has two subsidiary goals. The first is to suggest that the society for which Rawls provides a theory of justice is Western democracy, particularly in its twentieth century form - WD, for short. Rawls appeals to our intuition when W D nicely sums up what we have in common. Also he takes as natural attitudes which, if not exclusive to WD, are at least characteristic of it. The second subsidiary goal is to suggest that at the specific level o f Rawls's argument only a particular theory of justice is possible; a universal theory would be something quite distinct. Rawls is concerned mainly with the principles of social justice: "they provide a way o f assigning rights and duties in the basic institutions of society and they define the appropriate distribution of the benefits and burdens of social cooperation" (J4). The basic institutions are "the polit- ical constitution and the principal economic and social arrangements" (J7). The particular principles for which Rawls argues are: first, "Each Theory and Decision 4 (1974) 311-324. All Rights Reserved Copyright �9 1974 by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht-Holland 3 1 2 P H I L I P P E T T I T person is to have an equal right to the most extensive total system of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar system of liberty for all" 0250); second, "Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are both (a) to the greatest benefit of the least advantaged and (b) attached to otfices and positions open to all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity" (J83; for a later reading see J302). These princi- ples are interpreted under the constraints of two priority rules: roughly, that the first principle may never be compromised out of consideration for the second and that, in the case of the second, fair equality of oppor- tunity may never be restricted out of consideration for the greatest benefit o f the least advantaged 0302-03). Rawls argues for these principles of justice by a version of the contrac- tual theory. "They are the principles that free and rational persons con- cerned to further their own interests would accept in an initial position of equality as defining the fundamental terms of their association" (J11; see also Jl18-19). Rawls does not resort to a quasi-historical myth of a state of nature to give substance to his idea of the original position. It is a purely hypothetical situation defined by certain constraints and, taking account o f the constraints, we are meant to be able to simulate the reflec- tions of the imaginary contractors 0120). The constraints which define the original position include constraints on the parties - they are to be rational, representative of possible social positions, mutually disinterested, reliable when it comes to complying with the principles and so on; these, and constraints on the task in hand - the principles to be chosen are principles of social justice, the society in which they are to apply is one o f moderate scarcity, the principles are to satisfy such formal constraints as generality and publicity, etc. 0146-47). The central constraint however, is that of the veil of ignorance. This requires that the parties to the contract be in ignorance o f their particular talents and fortunes in the society for which they are choosing principles, and indeed be in ignorance of the particular historical circumstances of that society - their knowledge extends only to general facts of politics, economics and psychology (J137). The original position, by the present argument, is not a device which enables the theorist to step outside the limits of his place and time in history. It does not give him a voice to speak for men o f cultures far removed from his own. This its inventor fails to appreciate: " t o see our A T H E O R Y OF J U S T I C E ? 3 1 3 place in society from the peispective of this position is to see it sub specie aeternitatis: it is to regard the h u m a n situation n o t only from all social but also from all temporal points o f view" (J587). I I There are two lines which my argument might take. The first I will mention but not develop. It is the argument t h a t the very idea o f the original position makes sense only against the background o f a certain social experience. It presupposes the experience o f a society where the distri- bution o f social and economic goods is regarded as something subject to h u m a n agency (1). More deeply perhaps, it presupposes the experience o f social mobility and the uncertainty t h a t this brings with it; otherwise the veil of ignorance constraint would seem quite outlandish. The point I a m making is reminiscent o f C. B. MacPherson's claim t h a t the state o f nature o f which Locke (or Hobbes) spoke reflected a society in which market relations are d o m i n a n t so that " t h e individual with which he starts has already been created in the image o f market m a n " (Possessive Individualism, Oxford 1962, p. 269). I am arguing t h a t the contractors with which Rawls starts also show signs o f socially specific modelling: they are limit cases o f socially mobile individuals considering a problem characteristic o f a society t h a t allows some economic inter- vention by the state. I f this is so then some d o u b t is cast on the universal status o f Rawlsian theory. I do no more t h a n mention this point because I do n o t think t h a t it can be pressed home. The contractual theorist can say t h a t t h o u g h the original position is modelled on a situation specific to a certain society, there is no logical reason why it should n o t make sense in other societies. It is true t h a t there is no reason in logic w h y it should n o t do so - but there is every psychological reason why it should not. The idea o f the original position is t o o m u c h the flower of one society - as I see it, W D - to have m u c h chance o f blooming in others, at least in some others. In the f o u r t h section I shall mention a further consideration which suggests this view. The line o f argument which I prefer to follow n o w concentrates on the details o f the choice attributed to the contractors. The choice is t h a t o f the two principles o f justice and it is presented as " t h e unique solution to the problem set by the original position" (J119). I wish to argue t h a t 314 P H I L I P P E T T I T Rawls makes a case for this conclusion which there is no reason to think would carry equal weight in all societies. Rawls's b o o k falls into three parts: on 'theory', 'institutions' and 'ends'. In each of these parts he provides a description which is meant to justify the choice he attributes to the original contractors. In the first part he describes the choice as the implementation of the maximin decision proce- dure, in the second as the adoption o f principles in reflective equilibrium with our considered judgments of justice and in the third as the rational choice in view o f the contractors' conception of goodness. The three descriptions recur in the book, but each is defended in its respective part. I I I The maximin procedure is defined by a conservative rule for choice under uncertainty. "The maximin rule tells us to rank alternatives by their worst possible outcomes: we are to adopt the alternative the worst outcome of which is superior to the worst outcomes of the others" (J152-53). What Rawls wishes to argue is (a) that the choice of his two principles o f justice by the parties in the original position is a maximin procedure and (b) that as such it is the appropriate procedure in the original position. He puts some faith in this argument: "if the original position has been described so that it is rational for the parties to adopt the conservative attitude expressed by this rule a conclusive argument can indeed be con- structed for these principles" (J153). A b o u t (a): Rawls can show that choice o f his principles would be a maximin procedure only by comparing those principles with alternatives. He finds the alternatives in " a short list of traditional conceptions of justice" (J122). The conceptions he considers are mainly variants of utilitarianism: in particular he considers the principle that average utility- which, unlike aggregate utility, is insensitive to size of population - should be maximised. Here it is already clear that the reflections with which the contractors are credited are not very radical anthropologically: they are reflections traditional in WD. But perhaps the difficulty of the task does excuse these "rough and ready methods" (J123). Rawls now has to show that choice of the two principles represents the maximin procedure, that the worst outcome o f these two principles is better than the worst outcome of alternative procedures. His case has A T H E O R Y OF J U S T I C E ? 315 some plausibility. A high average utility might m a r k a society which tolerated slavery and the worst outcome for an individual in such a society - being a slave - would seem to be worse t h a n anything allowed in a society ordered by the two principles o f justice; the criteria for this assessment o f slavery certainly reflect a specific social experience, b u t I a m willing to grant t h a t they might be accepted by people o f any back- ground. The straight principle of average utility however is n o t the only utilitarian alternative to Rawls' principles. J. E. J. A l t h a m has suggested this further alternative to me: "maximise average utility, subject to first having satisfied needs". It is n o t at all clear t h a t the worst outcome of this would be worse t h a n the worst outcome o f the two principles o f justice. I am n o t anxious however to get stuck on this point. Let us grant t h a t choice o f the two principles does represent the maximin procedure. The second point which Rawls has to establish is t h a t in the original position, the maximin procedure is indeed the rational one. He draws on economic decision theory a n d argues t h a t in any situation there are three features which we must obtain if 'maximining' is to be the rational course. They are, t h a t the situation be one o f uncertainty within which probabili- ties c a n n o t be assigned to the possible outcomes o f any plan; t h a t the m i n i m u m outcome promised by the maximin rule be satisfactory; and t h a t some o f the outcomes o f alternative plans be unacceptable 0154). The A l t h a m alternative does n o t involve any unacceptable outcomes b u t again I put this aside. Let us assume t h a t these three conditions are realised in the original position. This brings us to the central question. G r a n t e d t h a t maximinning does m e a n choosing the two principles o f justice, granted too t h a t the original position satisfies the conditions which normally make maximinning the rational course, would choice o f the two principles necessarily seem the rational choice for the contractors to m a k e ? H o w would it seem to someone o f an aristocratic society for example, someone w h o f o u n d duelling regrettable perhaps but on m a n y occasions the only reasonable course? N o n e o f us can say for sure. A n d t h a t is precisely the point. It is only i f we presuppose in the contractors a certain attitude to risk - one which contrasts the p r u d e n t a n d the imprudent, n o t the mean and the m a n l y - t h a t the maximin rule will seem the rational procedure for them to adopt. We readily make t h a t presupposition because in W D we are generally disposed to take a conservative attitude to risk. 316 P H I L I P P E T T I T Rawls claims, contrary to this objection, t h a t his argument does n o t rest directly on the assumption o f an aversion to risk a m o n g the contrac- tors. " W h a t must be shown is that choosing as i f one h a d such an aversion is rational given the unique features o f t h a t situation irrespective o f any special attitudes to risk" (J172). This begs the question as it supposes t h a t there is some independent test o f the rational. A t this stage, the only test is whether we can simulate the reflections o f the parties in adopting the maximin procedure and feel their weight. This we can do with ease but only because o f our characteristic attitude to risk. A little historical imagination enables us to see t h a t others might find a very different rule o f choice the natural one for the contractors to follow. There is only one situation - one version o f the original position - in which it is h a r d to imagine that people o f a n y society would find the conservative rule o f choice unnatural. This would arise i f each contractor h a d to assume, n o t t h a t he might, but t h a t he definitely would be in the least advantaged position in the society to come. In this case the principle 'I cut, y o u choose' would apply (2). It would leave the choice o f the maximin alternative contingent, n o t on a particular attitude to risk, but on an attitude to coming out worst. This would be an advantage insofar as aversion to coming out worst seems to be a more natural and universal h u m a n attitude t h a n aversion to risk-taking. It would undermine the idea o f a contract however: a contractor could not assume t h a t he would be in the least advantaged position i f he recognised t h a t every other contractor made the same assumption. I V The second description which Rawls gives o f the choice which he imputes to the contractors presents the principles chosen as principles in reflective equilibrium with our considered judgments o f justice. They are in equilib- rium because the conclusions which they yield a b o u t h o w to organise the basic institutions o f a society are in line with our intuitive j u d g m e n t s ; the equilibrium is described as reflective because it gives us a view o f the grounds and mode o f derivation o f those judgments (J20). Rawls does n o t say t h a t the principles must in every case generate con- clusions in line with our judgments. In central cases they will. In marginal cases where we are n o t sure o f our judgments they m a y not: here the con- clusions m a y shift our intuitive judgments somewhat, providing us with A T H E O R Y OF J U S T I C E 9. 3 1 7 independent theoretical guidance (J19-20). The theory of justice is Socratic: "we m a y want to change our present considered judgments once their regulative principles are brought to light" (J49). The i m p o r t a n t point however is t h a t in the main, the t h e o r y fits our considered judg- ments. This fit is invoked by Rawls to justify the two principles which he takes the contractors to choose. " O n e can work out their consequences for institutions and note their implications for fundamental social policy. In this way they are tested by a comparision with our considered judgments o f justice" 0152). I do n o t intend to go into the consequences which Rawls draws f r o m his principles: they are consequences which describe W D in fair outline. W h a t I want to point out is t h a t the test o f reflective equilibrium is inconsistent with a 'universalist' view o f the theory o f justice. This test ensures t h a t what Rawls' theory does is explicate the sense o f justice d o m i n a n t a m o n g those whose judgments are taken into account, system- atise the principles t h a t they find natural and attractive. There is no more reason to believe t h a t one theory o f justice would satisfy all cultures t h a n there is to believe t h a t all cultures share the same judgments o f justice. Rawls provides a theory which answers only to our judgments, a theory o f justice for WD. (3) Rawls does try to give scientific status to the test o f reflective equilib- rium, and this m a y seem to do something for the status of his theory o f justice. He points out - rightly, I think - t h a t such a test also appears in linguistics, at least as described by N o a m Chomsky. " I n this case the aim is to characterise the ability to recognise well-formed sentences by formulating clearly expressed principles which m a k e the same discrimina- tions as the native speaker" (J47). Here too the theory is Socratic, the principles m a y influence our intuitive j u d g m e n t s : "while we m a y n o t expect a substantial revision o f our sense o f correct g r a m m a r in view o f a linguistic theory the principles o f which seem especially natural to us, such a change is n o t inconceivable, and no d o u b t our sense o f grammati- calness m a y be affected to some degree anyway by this knowledge" (J49). The analogy with linguistics however is a give-away. The analogy Rawls draws is with a particular grammar, the g r a m m a r o f a particular language. It suggests t h a t what he offers himself is a particular t h e o r y o f justice, the theory which explicates a particular sense o f justice. He might have f o u n d a less embarrassing analogue in universal grammar, the theory o f 3 1 8 P H I L I P P E T T I T the constraints under which all particular grammars must work. The trouble is that his theory does not have the required similarities with that grammar. It just is not a universal theory of justice. A further interesting point is suggested by the linguistic analogy: it links up with the argument mentioned in the second section but not developed. In Chomsky's linguistics, the descriptive adequacy of a gram- mar is its capacity to generate all and only the grammatical sentences of a language - the fact that it is in reflective equilibrium with our sense of grammaticalness. The drawback with descriptive adequacy as a criterion of a grammar however is that there may be two grammars which are capable of generating the grammatical sentences of a language. Chomsky finds a further criterion, a procedure for evaluating two descriptively adequate grammars, in universal grammar: the one which fits in better with the universal theory of language is the better grammar. It now has explanatory adequacy as well as descriptive (Aspects of the Theory of Syntax, Cambridge, Mass. 1965, pp. 26-27). The question is, does Rawls have any corresponding procedure for choosing between two theories of justice? He needs such a procedure, for it is at least conceivable that another theory of justice should also meet the test of reflective equilibrium. Why should a theory not be possible which set up a divine legislator and gave him such attributes that his imagined judgments on justice would be in reflective equilibrium with our own? H o w would Rawls decide then be- tween such a theory and that which he defends himself? Clearly he would decide for his own; so, I suspect, would all of us. But why? The only reason I can see, in the absence of a universal theory of justice which would do the work of Chomsky's universal theory, is that Rawls' theory is a native flower in WD, the alternative an exotic growth; here I return to the argu- ment of the second section. A myth of rational contractors in an original position is a more plausible myth to our minds than the myth of a divine legislator. V The third description which Rawls gives of the choice of the two principles o f justice presents it as the rational choice for the contractors in view of their conception of goodness. Does this description do any more than the others to give universal status to the Rawlsian theory of justice? I am A T H E O R Y OF J U S T I C E ? 319 going to argue that it does not because I do not think that RaMs estab- lishes the validity of this description. First, what does he mean by 'rational'? He takes his cue from the economic theory of decision-making. "Thus, in the usual way, a rational person is thought to have a coherent set of preferences between the op- tions open to him. He ranks these options according to how well they further his purposes; he follows the plan which will satisfy more of his desires rather than less, and which has the greater chance of being success- fully executed" (J143). Here RaMs gives us the three main principles that he thinks of as guiding rational choice: the principles of effective means, inclusiveness and greater likelihood (J411-12). The principles are useful because they enable us to compare different plans; they may even be allowed a universal appeal and validity. What they do not do however is mark out one plan as the rational one in a situation of choice - at least not necessarily. Hence they cannot in themselves determine the choice of the original contractors. What more is necessary in a situation of choice if one plan is to stand out as the rational plan ? First, Rawls says, that the requirement of delib- erative rationality is met. A plan is chosen with deliberative rationality when all its consequences have been clearly foreseen and balanced against the consequence of alternative plans (J417). Even when this requirement is met, however, it is not possible to say what is the rational plan for an individual in a situation of choice; that plan has only been specified formally. What it is also necessary to know is the desires which weigh with that individual. Thus if we are to be convinced that the rational plan for the original contractors to choose is represented by the two principles of justice we must be told something about their desires, their conception of the good. The distinctive thing however about the choice which faces the contrac- tors is that they do not, and in simulating their reflections we do not, know anything of their particular desires; this, by the veil of ignorance condition. The contractors are to choose principles of social organisation, not out of concern for such individually variable desires, but out of con- cern for desires to which they are bound, regardless of who they are. These are described as "general desires" (J263) or desires for "primary goods" (J93): they are meant to be desires for conditions required for the pursuit of any particular goals. 320 P H I L I P P E T T I T Rawls maintains, that these conditions, the primary goods, are certain rights and liberties, opportunities and powers, income and wealth and - something supposed to be made possible in the pursuit of these - self- respect (J92). He also maintains that these are ordered so that liberty is prior to socio-economic advantage and equality of opportunity to econ- omic welfare (J302-03); other motivational assumptions, e.g. that in- centive requires inequality, I leave unexamined. If his claims are allowed, then it certainly follows that Rawls's third description is a fair account of the choice which he imputes to the contractors; this is indeed the rational choice for them to make in view of their desires, their conception o f the good. Does Rawls justify his claims, does he establish his list of the primary goods? He certainly sets out a strategy for doing so. They are meant to be the goods to which the contractors are directed in view of certain "general facts" about human beings 0424). These include facts about human desires and wants, capacities and abilities, and social interdepen- dence: they are not discussed - on the grounds that they are matters of "common sense knowledge" (J425). The only fact discussed is described as a "deep psychological fact" (J432). "It says only that we prefer, other things equal, activities that depend upon a larger repertoire of realized capacities and that are more complex" (J429-30). Rawls calls it the Aristotelian principle. It is worth noting one reason why Rawls may feel free to pass so quietly over facts that play a crucial role in his theory. It is that he shows a not unexpected faith in psychology, an optimism about the invariability of the facts which this discipline may be presumed to catalogue. Thus he speaks of general psychological principles of which he allows his contrac- tors to be aware (J24, 456), principles which include "laws of motivation" 026). In doing so he backs up his assumption that men of any society would attribute to the contractors in the original position the same psychology that he gives them. His positivism on this issue begs the question of whether the original position makes possible a theory to explicate a universal sense of justice. But even if we grant Rawls his general facts - and what they are is not at all clear - we find that he fails to clinch his argument that they would lead the contractors to recognise the primary goods that he lists. At the point where we expect to have the argument clinched he falls back on A T H E O R Y OF J U S T I C E . 9 321 self-evidence. " W e must assume, then, t h a t the list o f p r i m a r y goods can be accounted f o r b y the c o n c e p t i o n o f goodness as rationality in con- nection with the general facts a b o u t h u m a n wants an d abilities, their characteristic phases and requirements o f nurture, the Aristotelian prin- ciple, and the necessities o f social interdependence .... I shall n o t argue the case for the list o f p r i m a r y goods here, since their claims seem evident e n o u g h " 0434). Rawls's failure to argue this case means his failure t o establish the validity o f his third description o f the choice at t ri b u t ed t o the contractors. It means that t h a t description does n o m o r e t h a n the others to establish the universal status o f his t h e o r y o f justice. VI But in fairness: R a M s does offer an argument f o r the necessity o f one p r i m a r y g o o d - t h a t o f self-respect. H e defines self-respect as (a) having a sense o f the value o f one's plan in life and (b) having confidence in one's ability to carry it out. He appeals to intuition in defence o f the idea t h at this is a p r i m a r y good. " W i t h o u t it n o t h i n g m a y seem w o r t h doing, or i f some things have value for us, we lack the will t o strive f o r t h e m " 0440). One can see the force o f this appeal in some cases, t h a t o f a profes- sional m a n in W D for instance, b u t one asks whether it applies in all. R a M s thinks t h a t it does and argues that each p erso n must find something he is g o o d at - and, to satisfy the Aristotelian principle, it had b et t er be o f some complexity - and f o r which he earns the respect o f some g r o u p o f people, respect which encourages him in self-respect. " T h u s w h at is necessary is t h a t there should be for each perso n at least one c o m m u n i t y o f shared interests to which he belongs and where he finds his endeavours confirmed by his associates" (J442; see also J178-79). This definition o f self-respect is tied in one obvious respect t o a n o n - universal p a t t e r n o f social experience, a p a t t e r n characteristically exem- plified in W D . It is individualist. I suggest that fo r societies in which the category o f the individual received less emphasis, fo r societies where social facts were n o t presumed in the n o r m t o be the o u t c o m e o f free individual actions, this definition would n o t do. Th e definition does n o t m a k e it a condition o f self-respect that one should see oneself as p a r t o f a larger entity - the g r o u p - in which one believes. This might well a p p e a r to be a condition o f self-respect to s o m e b o d y socialised in a m o r e tightly 322 PHILIP P E T T I T integrated society t h a n WD. But Rawls leaves no r o o m for such a person in his original position. His very definition o f society - " a cooperative venture for m u t u a l a d v a n t a g e " (J84) - must alienate anyone of a collec- tivist mentality f r o m the t h o u g h t experiment o f the original position. To get contractors into the original position in the hope o f simulating their reflections, it appears t h a t we are to bring t h e m t h r o u g h the p u r g a t o r y of WD. Rawls' concept of self-respect is i m p o r t a n t because he tries to derive an a r g u m e n t f r o m it for the priority - and indeed the basic appeal - o f liberty. 'Liberty' includes a variety o f freedoms: the freedom to vote and stand for public office, the freedom of thought, speech and assembly, the freedom o f person and (personal) property, freedom f r o m arbitrary arrest (J61); these, and also apparently " t h e i m p o r t a n t liberty of free choice o f occupation" (:I274). Rawls does n o t comment on the heterogeneous appearance o f the list. In general, liberty is something generated by institutional arrangements - a " p a t t e r n o f social f o r m s " (:I63) - and it has the merit o f p r o m o t i n g self-respect. Rawls argues t h a t in the society which the contractors foresee equal liberty is a sure basis for self-respect, one which n o b o d y would want to compromise, even in the hope o f material advantage. It is a basis o f self- respect because o f what it allows: " t h e full and diverse internal life o f the m a n y free communities o f interests" (J554; see also J442). A n d also, apparently, by a shift in the concept o f self-respect, it is meant to provide such a basis in its own right. " T h e basis for self-esteem in a just society is n o t then one's income share but the publicly affirmed distribution o f f u n d a m e n t a l rights and liberties. A n d this distribution being equal, every- one has a similar a n d secure status when they meet to conduct the c o m m o n affairs o f the wider society" (:I544). Against this it must be said t h a t the connection between liberty and self-respect cannot be p u t up as one t h a t must c o m m a n d universal assent, even when self-respect is defined in an individualistic way. There can be m a n y communities o f interest, enough to give everybody a chance o f self- expression, in a society which we would n o t regard as free. A n d there m a y also be sufficient matter for self-respect at the general political level. One might argue t h a t in a society terrorised by a dictatorial power, one would n o t have much r o o m for self-respect o f a n y kind. But the argument can hardly go to show the need for full political liberty in the Rawlsian sense - A T H E O R Y O F J U S T I C E . 9 323 certainly n o t something like liberty o f occupation. Liberty f r o m arbitrary arrest m a y be p u t in the same list as other 'liberties', but this does n o t make it o f a kind with them. Rawls himself mentions the possibility o f a feudal or caste society in which individuals find a source o f self-respect in the role given them in the order o f things. He says that this is an acceptable guarantee o f self-respect only because o f the assumption t h a t the order o f things is n o t subject to h u m a n choice, an assumption which is ruled out by the nature o f the enterprise on h a n d (J547). On the contrary: the only assumption necessary is t h a t the order of things in question has the most to be said for it in view o f the primary goods recognised by the contractors. Only by begging the question can equal liberty be taken to be one o f those goods. V I I The conclusion I draw is that Rawls does n o t establish that universal status which he assumes belongs to his theory o f justice. The contractual device gives the principles o f justice as o u t p u t only because the input is a socially specific mentality - the mentality, I suggest, o f people in WD. It will n o t do to say that the device gives even the general outline o f a "finally adequate t h e o r y " (J581). It can only give the outline o f a t h e o r y adequate to a particular sense of justice. The reason for this should n o w be clear. It is not any dialectical inca- pacity in Rawls but a reason in principle. I f a theory o f justice is meant to generate judgments o f justice satisfying the test o f reflective equilibrium then it is going to be relative to the set o f judgments, the particular sense o f justice, with which it tries to achieve equilibrium. A theory o f this kind c a n n o t assume universal status. But there is no scandal here. I do n o t see what is wrong with saying t h a t the sense o f justice by which we order - or at least criticise - our society reflects the image o f m a n we have created and n o t an eternal h u m a n essence. I do n o t see w h y theory should give itself the task o f rescuing t h a t sense o f justice from history. The t h e o r y o f justice is the means by which we explicate and examine our sense o f justice, it is n o t a means o f providing it with metaphysical foundations. The linguistic analogy suggests t h a t we should have a universal t h e o r y o f justice as well as a particular; this would describe the constraints which a n y theory of justice must meet. The best candidate for the title o f uni- 324 P H I L I P P E T T I T v e r s a l t h e o r y is t h e t r a d i t i o n a l p h i l o s o p h y o f j u s t i c e - t h e m e t a t h e o r y o f m o r a l s a n d politics. W h a t prescriptivists a n d descriptivists d o f o r i n s t a n c e c a n b e d e s c r i b e d i n this w a y : t h e y f o r m u l a t e c o n d i t i o n s - o f f o r m a n d c o n t e n t - w h i c h e v e r y sense o f j u s t i c e - a n d , m o r e generally, e v e r y m o r a l sense - m u s t meet, c o n d i t i o n s w h i c h a n y p a r t i c u l a r t h e o r y o f justice m u s t respect. I n r e c e n t w o r k o n justice a n d m o r a l i t y , it is fair t o s a y t h a t w e h a v e h a d e n o u g h o f u n i v e r s a l t h e o r y . T h a t is w h y R a w l s ' s w o r k is so i n t e r e s t i n g a n d so c h a l l e n g i n g ; it offers a p a r t i c u l a r t h e o r y o f o u r sense o f justice. I t is o n l y a p i t y t h a t R a w l s h i m s e l f s h o u l d h a v e c o n f u s e d it w i t h t h e o t h e r s o r t o f t h e o r y a n d tried t o c r e d i t it w i t h u n i v e r s a l status. Trinity Hall, Cambridge N O T E S * My warm thanks go to Jimmy Altham, Harry Bracken, Stefan Collini, Martin Hollis, Steven Lukes, Quentin Skinner and Denys Turner. Without their comments this paper would certainly have been a poorer effort. I am also grateful to Professor Rawls for a useful correspondence about his position. 1 I owe this point to Jimmy Altham. 2 I owe this point to Elizabeth Anscombe. 3 In WD there is wide disagreement on particular judgments of justice between politi- cally defined groups. I take it, with Rawls, that there is equally wide agreement on more general judgments, when the judgments are considered out of a political context. work_ikixekug6rck5lxbfubpqewl3i ---- Justice and Fairness in Negotiation Group Decis Negot (2017) 26:9–17 DOI 10.1007/s10726-016-9496-4 Justice and Fairness in Negotiation Daniel Druckman1,2,3 · Lynn Wagner4 Published online: 29 July 2016 © Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016 Abstract In this special issue we display a variety of approaches to the study of justice. Articles from scholars working on questions involving justice and fairness in decision making exchanges calls attention to a variety of research approaches, issue domains, cases and hypotheses used to explore these questions. All of the con- tributions emphasize analysis, using quantitative and qualitative methods including simulation-experiments, comparative case studies, statistical analyses and game the- ory. The articles in this collection reveal that justice and fairness concerns extend from the negotiation process to the outcome and into the implementation stage. They share the underlying expectation that individuals and groups gravitate toward fairness and justice in their exchanges with others. Therefore, a full understanding of group decision processes will be incomplete if justice and fairness issues are not consid- ered alongside issues such as power distributions and alternatives to an agreement. The authors also suggest that outcomes built on justice and fairness principles will enhance the efficiency, stability and implementation of the negotiated agreements. Keywords Distributive justice · Fairness · Negotiation process · Pareto-optimal allocations · Procedural justice B Daniel Druckman dandruckman@yahoo.com Lynn Wagner lynn@iisd.org 1 George Mason University, Farifax, VA, USA 2 Macquarie University, Sydney, Australia 3 The University of Queensland, Brisbane, Australia 4 International Institute for Sustainable Development, Winnipeg, Canada 123 http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1007/s10726-016-9496-4&domain=pdf 10 D. Druckman, L. Wagner 1 Introduction This special issue showcases the many faces of justice in negotiation. Articles from scholars working on questions involving justice and fairness in decision making exchanges expose the reader to a variety of research approaches, issue domains, cases and hypotheses used to explore these questions. Cutting across the contributions is a focus on analysis, using quantitative and qualitative methods including simulation- experiments, comparative case studies, statistical analyses and game theory. Cases addressing issues from security to environmental policy are examined through the lenses of a variety of theoretical perspectives. The articles address the sources, corre- lates, and contexts within which justice considerations are germane. As the articles in this collection reveal, justice plays a complex role in group deci- sion making. The articles explore the sources of justice claims, including the more psychological roots and the larger political context. These conceptions of justice are manifested in negotiation processes that involve decisions concerning which groups will be represented in the process, whether they will have access to relevant infor- mation and opportunities to speak in order to fully participate in the process, and whether the parties have a choice in accepting the final agreement. The agreement might represent a number of types of justice, from equal distributions of resources under discussion, to splitting the resources according to the parties’ inputs or needs, to compensating parties. Assessments of whether the process and outcome were just or fair influence negotiating parties’ attitudes toward the agreement, with implications for implementation. The articles seek to analyze these variables in order to enhance our understand- ing of how negotiators develop conceptions of justice and how justice considerations influence negotiation processes, outcomes and implementation of agreements. The objective of such an understanding is to enhance future decision making encounters; the final paper explicitly explores how fair (defined as envy-free and Pareto-optimal) allocations could be arrived at. Together, the articles reveal where justice claims come from, the relationship between these claims and outcomes, and the way the claims manifest in a variety of settings including legal negotiations, negotiating peace fol- lowing civil wars, maritime and territorial disputes, and environmental disputes. These articles are reviewed following an overview of the topic. 2 The Role of Justice In our recent article for the Annual Review of Psychology (Druckman and Wagner 2016), we situate justice in a broad framework of processes of and influences on negotiation. The article highlighted the importance of justice concepts in a variety of negotiations. For example, better agreements were obtained when simulated attorneys representing homeowners and contractors regarded the process as fair (Hollander- Blumoff and Tyler 2008) and when national representatives in historical negotiations adhered to principles of procedural justice (Wagner and Druckman 2012). More durable agreements occurred when peace negotiators adhered to equality principles in the outcomes (Albin and Druckman 2012). Further, the implementation of agreements 123 Justice and Fairness in Negotiation 11 are hypothesized to be facilitated when principles related to post-conflict justice, often referred to as transitional justice, guide the post-negotiation period (Binningsbø et al. 2012). The pre-negotiation period is critical for setting the tone in terms of such relational factors as shared identities and normative considerations that include agreement on procedural issues. By bolstering negotiators’ trust and confidence, these factors are likely to increase the chances for a lasting agreement. They also increase a group orientation that emphasizes problem-solving rather than competitiveness (see Lind and Tyler 1988). Interestingly, group-value negotiators also de-emphasize differences in power or use their power advantage to encourage adherence to procedural justice (PJ) principles which often lead to problem solving. A result of these processes is an agreement that embodies the distributive principle of equality. (See Cook and Hegtvedt 1983 for a distinction between the distributive principles of equality and equity.) Equality provisions in agreements bolster the shared identities established during the pre-negotiation stage and pave the way to smooth implementation. The key is to maintain adherence to the principles that guided the process and agreements. For agreements that end violence, this means transitioning from a state of war to peace. For agreements that resolve legal and workplace disputes, this means transitioning from conflictual to cooperative relationships. For both types of agreements, the changes are more likely to last when spoilers are not present during the implementation process (Stedman 2000). A stage conception of negotiation provides a lens for understanding justice con- cepts in terms of a linear path: pre-negotiation interactions encourage justice in the process which increases the chances for a stable agreement. An alternative conception views negotiation in terms of a system. This perspective captures bi-directional and cyclical effects of justice variables. It is attuned to the many ways in which justice variables influence and are influenced by the many other factors that operate in a larger negotiating environment. Rather than exploring historical trajectories of justice and relational variables, this approach focuses attention on an interplay among them as they operate together at any point in time. Rather than isolating justice as a focus for analysis, the approach situates justice in a dynamic social environment. Although the Welch article in this collection comes closest to this perspective, there have been few attempts to develop it as a framework for analysis (see Vallacher et al. 2010). 3 The Many Faces of Justice Justice comes in many forms. Although procedural and distributive justice are the primary forms studied by negotiation researchers, other type of justice receive atten- tion as well. A focus on the period of implementation highlights the role played by transitional justice (TJ). Considered usually in the context of civil war, TJ refers to justice during the transition from armed conflict to peace or from an authoritarian to a democratic political system. It may reinforce the justice principles that guided the negotiation process and outcome or veer away from those principles as agreements unfold. Studies on agreement durability address these matters (Albin and Druckman 2012; Wagner and Druckman, this issue). Another form of justice that receives atten- 123 12 D. Druckman, L. Wagner tion in the literature is referred to as restorative. This also deals with the post-agreement period and emphasizes ideas of restitution and apology. The large literature on truth and reconciliation commissions focuses primarily on this form of justice (see Hayner 2011) as does the research on acknowledgement and apology (Lewicki et al. 2016). A fifth form of justice is referred to as retributive, which focuses attention on the actions taken toward a victim and against a harms doer (Darley and Pittman 2003). This form emphasizes the distributive principle of compensation for wrong-doing and is central in the literature on criminal justice. It comes into play as well in discussions of restorative justice, where both negative, as in revenge, and positive, as in restitution, are weighed in decisions. Positive forms of compensation are discussed in the Wagner and DruckmanandAlbinandDruckmanarticlesinthisissue.Theyarealsodemonstratedin large-scale trade negotiations by Kapstein (2008). Whether negotiators and mediators are attuned to these distinctions among forms of justice or perceive the concept in holistic ways is an interesting research issue (see Hauenstein et al. 2001; also see the Welch article in this issue for a more holistic conception of justice) Another distinction refers to the way that justice is studied. The social science literature is divided between normative and descriptive approaches to the topic. The former divides into axiomatic and theoretical or philosophical approaches. Axiomatic studies seek to deduce fair or optimal solutions from stated preferences for alternative outcomes. Arrow (1963) early work on fairness provides a foundation for these studies. The approach is represented by the Brams, Kilgour, and Klamler article in this issue. Theoretical approaches have been inspired primarily by the writings of Rawls (1971). Considered as a work in political philosophy, Rawls offers a theory of society that adheres to the principle of “justice for all.” He attempts to reconcile liberty with equality by proposing a well-ordered society in which members cooperate to bring the greatest good for the greatest number of citizens. The prescriptive feature of the approach offers a path in the direction of optimal or integrative negotiating solutions, a goal sought as well by the axiomatic approaches. Descriptive approaches divide into experimental and case studies. Both seek to discover the way that justice principles impact on decisions made in negotiation and related arenas. Laboratory studies focus on the conditions under which particular justice principles emerge. For example, the debate between equity (Adams 1965) and equality (Deutsch 1985) theorists on when one or the other of these distributive justice (DJ) principles guide decisions has benefitted from experimental findings. Similarly, the debates about procedural justice issues have been enlightened by experimental findings as illuminated by Hollander-Blumoff’s article in this issue. Case studies have been more concerned with contexts for negotiation. Justice matters are understood in terms of histories of relationships and types of issues being contested. This is illustrated by the three comparative studies in this issue, where justice is explored in the context of terminating civil wars as well as in attempts to resolve territorial and environmental disputes. The situational and contextual lenses provided by experimental and case study approaches are complementary. Together they contribute to the development of a larger theory of justice. The empirical basis for that theory may also be enriched by developments on the normative front. Rawls’ theory of society and the Brams et al algorithms for deducing optimal solutions add insights to those discovered in the laboratory and field. 123 Justice and Fairness in Negotiation 13 4 Articles in this Issue The five articles in this issue offer insights into justice from different perspectives, methodologicalapproaches,andissueareas.Simulation-experiments,statisticalanaly- ses of cases, a small number of cases for comparison, and a game-theoretic approach are represented. Justice is studied in the contexts of legal disputes, a sampling of peace agreements, regional territorial conflicts, and cases of environmental negotiations. The key insights from each article are summarized in this section. In her article on “Procedural Justice Judgments in Legal Negotiations,” Hollander- Blumoff explores the antecedents of procedural justice judgments in legal negotiation. Earlier PJ research has shown strong effects for PJ on negotiating behavior, and this research is extended by three of the articles in this issue. She attempts to dig deeper into this relationship by identifying what accounts for the finding. She compares four factors thought to influence PJ judgments: voice, courtesy/respect, trust, and neutral- ity. By including both self-report perceptions and third-party coding of video-taped behaviors, Hollander-Blumoff breaks new ground in this area of research. Few previ- ous studies include behavioral process assessments. Interestingly, she obtains similar results from both types of assessments. Courtesy-respect is found to be the strongest driver of PJ judgments in both the self-report and behavioral data. The importance of courtesy-respect calls attention to the relevance of interpersonal relational rather than more substantive influence of PJ judgments. But it is interesting to note that voice also plays a role in these judgments albeit somewhat less strongly. This finding com- ports with results from the Albin-Druckman study discussed below. Their analyses of archival documents from negotiations show that fair representation (voice) largely accounts for the relationship between PJ and effectiveness in environmental negotia- tions. Hollander-Blumoff’s study contributes new insights into how PJ judgments are formed. She asks what specifically accounts for negotiator’s perception of a fair process. This approach is used also in the articles by Wagner and Druckman and Albin and Druckman. The former study isolated equality as the key type of DJ accounting for durable agreements and durable peace. As noted above the latter study found that fair representation was the key driver of effectiveness. These findings suggest justice may not be a global concept. Rather it is an aggregate of several parts that may have different effects in negotiation and during the post-negotiation period. The Hollander-Blumoff study is framed as exploratory. She discusses some lim- itations and next steps. One limitation is the single dependent variable (DV), which consists of a perception of PJ. Looking forward, her research would benefit from expanding the range of DVs examined including negotiating behavior and outcomes. An example is the earlier Hollander-Blumoff and Tyler (2008) study. A question of interest is: How does courtesy-respect encourage problem-solving behavior and inte- grative outcomes? In their article on “Drivers of Durable Peace: The Role of Justice in Negotiating Civil War Termination,” Wagner and Druckman develop a multidimensional index of durable peace (DP) following peace agreements. Considered in their research as a dependent variable, the index is used to evaluate the impacts of procedural and distributive justice on reconciliation and changes in societal institutions. Procedural 123 14 D. Druckman, L. Wagner justice consists of four parts that surface during the negotiation process: fair play, fair representation, transparency, and voluntary decisions. Distributive justice also consists of four parts that are reflected in the terms of agreement: equality, proportionality, compensation, and need. Their archival analyses of 16 peace agreements negotiated mostly in the 1990s produce a number of interesting findings. The DP index correlates strongly with a measure of the stability of the agreement (SA). More interesting, however, are the mediated effects involving the SA measure: Stable agreements are shown to mediate the relationship between the DJ principle of equality and DP. This variable also mediates the relationship between PJ and the reconciliation component of DP. Justice variables have a stronger influence on DP when the agreements are stable through time. The impacts on reconciliation and institutions do not include economic growth. That feature of DP is not found to be a dividend of peace agreements. These authors demonstrate that justice plays an important role in peace following civil wars. Adhering to PJ principles during negotiations and including equality prin- ciples in the agreement texts increase the chances for agreements that hold and for societal peace. More broadly, the findings suggest a link between negotiation processes at a micro level of analysis and peace at a macro level. This link highlights the rele- vance of negotiation to relations between state and non-state actors. It suggests that the way a peace agreement is negotiated has important ramifications for future relations between former combatants and for the institutions in which they participate during the post war period. Building on these findings, Wagner and Druckman have extended their sampling to 50 cases. We await the results from these analyses. Welch’s article on “The Justice Motive in East Asia’s Territorial Disputes” under- scores the importance of justice concerns in bilateral international disputes. His comparative case analyses show that conflicts can be difficult to resolve even when strategic or economic issues are negligible. Symbolic or ideational conflicts often trig- ger the justice motive, which can be regarded as an intervening variable between the type of issue at stake (symbolic or economic) and the likelihood of war. He points out that an inflamed sense of justice may be a necessary condition for conflict. This is demonstrated in four of the six cases that he examines. The two exceptions, the Hans Island and Machias Seal Island disputes, are territorial conflicts between countries with a history of cooperation and membership in a shared security community. For these countries, the territorial disputes are not salient political issues and devoid of serious justice claims. Interestingly, none of his cases are disputes spurred by economic or security claims. Although his limited sampling of cases raise issues of generalization to territorial conflicts elsewhere in the world, his analyses provoke important questions about justice for research with larger, more representative samples. These include: What makes justice disputes dangerous?, How might these dangers be reduced?, and What are the prospects of reducing them? With regard to his first question, Welch calls attention to the relevance of insights from behavioral economics, in particular the concept of reference points. The pain of perceived losses motivate people to persevere in support of a status quo that reinforces maintaining their right to the islands. With regard to his second and third questions, Welch proposes four mechanisms for settling these kinds of disputes: negotiation, persuasion, procedures, and rules. He concludes that the obstacles to settlement by any of these approaches are formidable but not prohibitive. For example, the dispute 123 Justice and Fairness in Negotiation 15 between Japan and South Korea over the Dokdo/Takeshima islands may be amenable to procedural solution. The willingness of China to negotiate a solution to the South China Sea conflicts is not matched by comparable willingness by any of its potential negotiating partners. The Albin and Druckman article on “Negotiating Effectively” asks whether negotia- tors who rely on justice principles in the process of bargaining and drafting agreements are more effective than those that are not guided by these principles. The answer is yes depending on the type of negotiation. Focusing on twenty international environmen- tal negotiations divided evenly between bilateral and multilateral cases, the authors analyze relationships between procedural and distributive justice on the one hand and effectiveness on the other. The justice variables are defined in a similar manner as was done in the Wagner and Druckman article in this issue; a difference however is that DJ was coded by Albin and Druckman in the negotiation process rather than the agree- ment as in Wagner and Druckman. Effectiveness is defined by these authors in terms of the extent of agreement (among parties and on issues), time to reach agreement, and comprehensiveness of the agreement. Their key finding is that adherence to PJ prin- ciples predicts effectiveness in the multilateral negotiations. This impact is stronger for the quality of the agreement than for the efficiency of the negotiating process. It is also stronger for fair representation than for the other PJ principles. Adherence to DJ principles during the bilateral negotiating process resulted in a more efficient process (in terms of time to agreement) but not better agreements. Also interesting is the finding that the two types of justice, assessed within the negotiation process, are only weakly related. The authors’ finding of contrasting effects for PJ in the bilateral and multilateral samples may highlight the challenges posed by large-scale conferences of organizing the process and developing trusting relationships in which the delegates appreciate their shared identities. Of particular interest are the roles played by fair representation (voice) and a lack of coercion in producing effective agreements. These aspects of PJ may increase perceptions of trust and shared identities among the delegates more than transparency and fair play. But the findings also have practical implications by identifying areas where multilateral conference organizers can apply their leverage on the process most effectively. Whether these implications apply as well to other multilateral issue areas remains a question to be addressed in further research. The final article by Brams, Kilgour and Klamler anchors the collection by pro- viding a prescriptive lens on issues of fairness. The authors’ game theory approach to determining whether an envy-free allocation exists reveals a condition that “guar- antees the existence of a maximin, envy free, and Pareto-optimal allocation.” These authors present a procedure for dividing a set of indivisible items that two parties value differently and can rank from best to worst. The procedure is expected to reveal allocations that the parties will view as fair and acceptable, and therefore lead to a constructive settlement of a dispute. While the real-world disputes examined in the other papers will not necessarily consist of fully identifiable issues that parties can easily rank from best to worst, many of the justice concepts studied in those papers aim to bring the dispute as close to this idealized situation as possible. Ensuring that all parties to the dispute are represented at the table and have access to relevant information – conditions for procedural justice 123 16 D. Druckman, L. Wagner – would go a long way toward producing an optimal or integrative solution. Disputing parties, including those with claims of procedural or distributive injustice, would have a full say in assessing the relative value of the issues under discussion and how they are to be divided to satisfy their desire for a fair outcome. While the impartiality that would accompany a strict application of Brams, Kilgour and Klamler’s algorithm would not be likely in a real-world application, mediators and parties could benefit by stepping back to consider the requirements of their process, and to ask whether any adjustments could be made to bring more justice to the process and solution options under discussion. Indeed, Welch stresses the necessity of such an assessment when he notes that any settlement of a territorial dispute would require that “claimants would not, on the basis of full information, consider the outcome unjust.” Brams, Kilgour and Klamler’s algorithm could be used as a standard for evaluating a range of proposed solutions to conflicts. 5 Conclusion The articles in this collection share the underlying expectation that individuals and groups gravitate toward fairness and justice in their exchanges with others. Hollander- Blumoff’s motivation to explore how individuals form judgments about the fairness of the process is based on research findings that “people care deeply about the fairness of proceduresusedtoresolvetheirdisputes.”Welchnotesthatthenegotiationofterritorial disputes would require an agreement that would involve “either a division of the stake or compensation adequate to allow one or both parties to convince themselves that relinquishing all or part of a title in return for something else was fair on balance,” which he suggests “is easier done in a context of good will and mutual respect.” Along these same lines, Albin and Druckman suggest that, given their findings that justice issues influence the direction of the process and the outcome, negotiation analyses need to take justice and related moral/ethical norms into account, rather than focus primarily on interests and power. A full understanding of group decision processes will be incomplete if justice and fairness issues are not considered alongside issues such as power distributions and alternatives to an agreement. The articles also share the underlying expectation that outcomes built on justice and fairness principles will enhance the stability and implementation of the agreements. The “maximin, envy free, and Pareto-optimal allocation” that could be revealed using the algorithm that Brams, Kilgour and Klamler present would leave the parties with the best joint outcome, which would make them less likely to attempt to return to the table to reallocate the resources at a subsequent time. Wagner and Druckman link the inclusion of justice in the agreement with the stability of peace agreements in the short term as well as the durability of the peace in the long term. Justice and fairness concerns extend from the negotiation process to the outcome and into the implementation stage. The papers included in this collection reveal that a variety of principles comprise the conceptions of justice and fairness, and vary from stage to stage. Nevertheless, it is possible to characterize and analyze these principles, through studies like those included in this collection, in order to provide 123 Justice and Fairness in Negotiation 17 a fuller understanding of group decision processes, their outcomes, and how likely these outcomes are to be implemented. Acknowledgements Many thanks are extended to Rebecca Hollander-Blumoff, William Donohue, Serdar Guner, P. Terrence Hopmann, William Maley, Valerie Rosoux, and Dean Tjosvold for serving as reviewers of the papers submitted for publication in this special issue. References Adams JS (1965) Inequity in social exchange. In: Berkowitz L (ed) Advances in experimental social psy- chology. Academic Press, New York Albin C, Druckman D (2012) Equality matters: negotiating an end to civil wars. J Confl Resolut 56(2):155– 182 Arrow KJ (1963) Social choice and individual values, 2nd edn. Yale University Press, New Haven Binningsbø HM, Loyle CE, Gates S, Elster J (2012) Armed conflict and post-conflict justice, 1946–2006: a dataset. J Peace Res 49(5):731–740 Cook KS, Hegtvedt KA (1983) Distributive justice, equity, and equality. Annu Rev Sociol 9:217–241 Darley JM, Pittman TS (2003) The psychology of compensatory and retributive justice. Personal Soc Psychol Rev 7(4):324–336 Deutsch M (1985) Distributive justice: a social psychological perspective. Yale University Press, New Haven Druckman D, Wagner L (2016) Justice and negotiation. Annu Rev Psychol 67:387–413 Hauenstein NMA, Mogonicle T, Flinder SW (2001) A meta-analysis of the relationship between procedural justice and distributive justice: implications for justice research. Empl Responsib Rights J 13(1):39–56 Hayner PB (2011) Unspeakable truths: Transitional justice and the challenge of truth commissions, 2nd edn. Routledge, New York Hollander-Blumoff R, Tyler TR (2008) Procedural justice in negotiation: procedural fairness, outcome acceptance, and integrative potential. Law Soc Inq 33(2):473–500 Kapstein EB (2008) Fairness considerations in world politics: lessons from international trade negotiations. Polit Sci Q 123(2):229–245 Lewicki RJ, Pollin B, Lount RB (2016) An exploration of the structure of effective apologies. Negot Confl Manag Res 9(2):177–196 Lind EA, Tyler TR (1988) The social psychology of procedural justice. Plenum Press, New York Rawls J (1971) A theory of justice. Harvard University Press, Cambridge Stedman S (2000) Spoiler problems in peace processes. In: Stern PC, Druckman D (eds) International conflict resolution after the Cold War. National Academy Press, Washington Wagner L, Druckman D (2012) The role of justice in historical negotiations. Negot Confl Manag Res 5(1):49–71 Vallacher R, Coleman PT, Nowak A, Bui-Wrzosinska L (2010) Rethinking intractable conflict: the perspec- tive of dynamical systems. Am Psychol 65(4):262–278 123 Justice and Fairness in Negotiation Abstract 1 Introduction 2 The Role of Justice 3 The Many Faces of Justice 4 Articles in this Issue 5 Conclusion Acknowledgements References work_ikmlzpulezaydap4qlra57lv6e ---- 1 Transitional justice as an elite discourse: Human rights practice between the global and the local in post-conflict Nepal Simon Robins 1 Post-war Reconstruction and Development Unit, University of York Abstract Nepal's conflict emerged as a result of a highly unequal society in which the indigenous, lower castes and women were subject to systematic social, political and economic exclusion. This study seeks to understand how post-conflict agendas to address Nepal‟s violent past emerge, and compares the agendas articulated by indigenous victims of the conflict from a remote rural district with that of civil society dominated by Kathmandu based elites. An empirical study has been made of the needs of transition of families of those disappeared during the conflict in the Mid-western district of Bardiya, the worst affected by disappearances during the Maoist insurgency. This agenda is then compared and contrasted with that articulated by those leading advocacy for transitional justice in Nepal, namely national and international human rights agencies. Indigenous rural victims remain ignorant of rights and articulate an agenda of addressing basic needs and demanding political change that empowers them. Elite led civil society, notably among human rights agencies, has adopted a highly legalistic agenda that coincides with the dominant global rights discourse in which prosecutorial process is prioritised and the inequalities that led to conflict considered beyond the remit of transitional justice; issues of social and economic rights are ignored. Victims remain marginalised from both the transitional process and from those agencies that purport to represent them. A global rights agenda that uses the language of giving agency to the marginalised actually serves to advance ethnic and caste based elites. Not to be quoted without permission of the author. Paper to be presented at the ISA Annual Convention 2010, New Orleans; Feb. 17 th -20 th 2010. Impacting Policy Makers: Conflict and Human Rights Panel 1 simon.robins@simonrobins.com 2 Introduction Transitional justice is an effort to respond to the needs of societies emerging from conflict or political violence 2 and has become the preferred lens through which to examine democratising states. Typically, these are institutional responses to violations of international humanitarian law, human rights law or domestic law that occurred during a previous regime. This discourse emerged from a legal tradition, parallel to that of human rights, and as such initially saw such responses as principally legal, concerning retributive justice and prosecution. 3 However, transitional justice has increasingly become dependent upon a broader understanding of the concept of justice that goes beyond prosecutorial mechanisms and includes mechanisms that aim to address issues of truth and reconciliation, reparations and acknowledgment. The justice of transitional justice has also been interpreted in its broadest sense, not only as a legal response, but as a multi-faceted process that seeks to build social relations perceived as equitable. 4 In this sense transitional justice can aim not just to address violations of the conflict and their consequences but the injustices that led to conflict. Such an interpretation has led to the beginnings of an engagement with issues such as development and social exclusion within the transitional justice discourse. 5 Much has been written critical of the human rights discourse from which transitional justice emerges, notably that it represents a wholly Western tradition, 6 and challenging its claims to universality. 7 Critiques of contemporary approaches to transitional justice are centred around its embodiment in institutional approaches, either national or supra-national, 8 its continuing dominance by a legalist agenda 9 and the fact that it is steered by perspectives deriving almost exclusively from elites. 10 Despite a widespread understanding that it is the poor and disempowered who suffer most in the violence that precedes transition and who constitute most of the victims of conflict, a sustained engagement with such constituencies has not become part of the mainstream practice of transitional justice. Whilst many transitional processes claim to be “victim-centred” (e.g. the much discussed transition in South Africa 11 ) this term remains under conceptualised and transitional processes continue to be driven largely by elites in concerned states with the support and guidance of the international community. In many post-conflict interventions both the individual and collective consequences of violations remain largely unexamined. The human rights discourse is now truly global, both in its stated universality and in the range of states that claim to enforce rights. However human rights has globalised together with other sets of norms, including a broad range of liberal, and sometimes neo-liberal, tenets. 12 In the developing world a discourse of development, rights and liberal democracy has become truly hegemonic, with international donors, NGOs and most governments claiming to ascribe to 2 Teitel 2000. 3 Teitel 2003; Orentlicher, 1991, 2007. 4 Kriesberg, 2001. 5 e.g. Mani 2008. 6 e.g. Pollis and Schwab 1989; Panikkar 1984. 7 e.g. Donnelly 1984. 8 Duschinski 2008. 9 McEvoy 2008. 10 McEvoy and McGregor 2008. 11 Republic of South Africa 1999. 12 Rajagopal 2003. 3 what are broadly perceived as universal values. The practice of human rights however remains far from universal: „on the ground‟ human rights is a transnational discourse that must compete with local political and other imperatives. As a result, the study of the practice of human rights is necessarily discursive; to understand how the global rights discourse impacts in particular places upon human actors, given the webs of political and social relationships in which it must operate. 13 The study of rights in practice involves studying how the global discourse of rights is instantiated or constituted in a particular context. Here that context is a conflict affected district of Nepal, remote and rural and with a majority indigenous population. An empirical study has been made as to how the human rights discourse is articulated in this post-conflict setting and how visions of transitional justice arising from that discourse coincide with or contradict those of conflict affected indigenous people. This article begins from the understanding both that there is no such thing as human rights „in the abstract‟, 14 and that „non-elites [...] are very often important human rights theorists‟ 15 . This article aims to ask where the global discourse of human rights is situated or constituted, and how does the way these norms are constructed in practice impact upon the emancipatory potential of that discourse, in particular in a highly unequal society in transition from armed conflict. This highlights the difference between human rights on a conceptual level, the global and the universal idea that drives the discourse, and how they are instantiated in particular social settings, subject to the power relations that exist between the actors involved. 16 Nepal‟s conflict was the product of a society built upon the codified exclusion of a majority of its people. Such social exclusion 17 militates against the engagement of a large fraction of Nepalese in many areas of society, on the basis of caste, ethnicity and gender: it is unsurprising that it also impacts on the transition from conflict. Post-conflict efforts to create transitional justice mechanisms continue to be elite led and to marginalise victims and their agendas, and to be dominated by a narrow legalism that neglects the priorities of victims. The ethnographic research discussed here appears to confirm that the idea and meaning of rights in this transitional context is a product of the conjunction of victims with needs and a global discourse articulated by elites. However, the norms that emerge refer far more to priorities internal to the discourse itself than to the needs or agenda of victims, largely because one is articulated by the powerful and one by the powerless: „human rights is not a product of social relations but immanent in them, internal to their very expression [...] rights are positioned at the conjuncture of the two fields of the social: agency and power‟ 18 The aim here is not to devalue human rights discourse in transitional contexts, but to enrich it by demonstrating that rights are mediated by the actors who articulate them: in an unequal society, as any other discourse, they will become subject to existing power relations. 13 Goodale and Merry 2007. 14 Ibid, 25. 15 Ibid. 16 e.g. Stammers 1999. 17 de Haan 1998. 18 Wilson 1997. 4 The Tharu of Bardiya: Exclusion and victimisation Bardiya and the Tharu Nepal is the poorest country in Asia, and the 12 th poorest in the world, 19 with an annual income per capita barely over $400 per year: 30% of the population lives on less than $1 per day. The feudal social relations that have persisted into modern times impact upon livelihoods, with a significant fraction of the rural population being landless and working as sharecroppers for landlords. A lack of access to land is the dominant cause of rural poverty. Nepal is a mosaic of ethnicities, languages and castes, having a unique and complex ethnic geography. The kingdom of Nepal was unified in the 18 th century, under a dynasty of peoples who migrated from India in the centuries before. They established themselves as an elite, socially, culturally, economically and racially, through a rigid system of social stratification that placed the Brahmin and Chhetri castes of the migrants above both the indigenous ethnicities and lower Hindu caste groups. 20 As a result of this social exclusion, traditionally non-Hindu indigenous people (Janajati) and more recent immigrants into the Terai plains of Nepal from neighbouring India, have been systematically excluded from the very idea of the Nepali nation, with many traditionally being denied citizenship. As a result, a majority of the population have been excluded from certain parts of the economy, from what little social services are available and from politics. Indigenous people and the lowest castes face mortality, literacy and income far below the nation‟s meagre average. 21 Within families and communities most of Nepal‟s cultures relegate women to a subservient role, and women have been largely absent from decision making at all levels. Bardiya is one of Nepal‟s 75 districts, lying in the Terai on its border with India in the Mid-west development region. Predominantly rural, Bardiya is a district of agriculturalists and one of only two where the indigenous Tharu people are a majority. The Tharu constitute around 6.75% of the population of Nepal, 1.5 million people, of whom 83% work in agriculture. 22 Indicators of their exclusion can be seen in education: Tharu literacy rates are half (17.5%) the rate among non-Tharu in Bardiya. 23 The Tharu are traditionally animists and have their own language (or languages) and unique medicinal and spiritual traditions. 24 As a result of efforts to assimilate the indigenous peoples into a narrowly defined Nepali identity, many Tharu now consider themselves Hindu, but continue to practice non-Hindu traditions 25 . In the last three decades of the 20 th century the Nepali Government encouraged migrants from the hills, mainly high caste Hindus who shared language and culture with the ruling elite, to migrate to the Terai to exploit land from which malaria had recently been eradicated. 26 High caste migrants were readily able to capture political power because of their education, wealth and access to local authorities with whom they shared ethnicity. For the Tharu 19 UNDP 2004. 20 Höfer 2004. 21 UNDP 2004. 22 Danida 2004. 23 Chhetri 2005: 25. 24 Guneratne 2004. 25 During this research a Tharu woman was asked what her religion was, at which point she turned to the other women with her and asked “Are we Hindu or Muslim?”. This well summarises the relationship many indigenous people have with the dominant religion of Nepal. 26 Conway, Bhattarai and Shrestha 2000. 5 this began what they perceive as the systematic theft of their land, their only economic capital, by migrants, leaving many dispossessed and farming as tenants or share croppers. Most notably, land was seized following the making of loans to Tharu landowners with interest arrangements that ensured payment was impossible. 27 The result of this was the creation of a class of bonded labourers among the Tharu, known as kamaiya: entire families constrained for generations to work for a landlord to pay off debts. 28 Control of land passed to high caste landowners, who then employed the Tharu to work the land. Tharu marginalisation was enhanced by their lack of political representation and minimal presence in the institutions of the state. Conflict between the Tharu and the incoming migrants over land had occurred since migration began with the Nepali state violently intervening in support of landlords. 29 A dominant strand of the Tharu land rights movement was that to „free‟ the kamaiya, and the democratic changes of 1990 eventually led to the Government outlawing this form of contemporary slavery in 2000 and adopting the Kamaiya Labour Prohibition Act in 2002. 30 However, both the freed kamaiya and many other Tharu families own no land and must rely on casual work, share cropping or tenancy to survive. For many in Bardiya, both among the Tharu and high caste landlords, the Maoist „People‟s war‟ was another episode in this ongoing conflict over land. The development discourse and exclusion Despite the limited state presence in much of rural Nepal, people were exposed to an idea of Nepal and of being Nepali constructed by elites in their own image. This disseminated the culture and values of that elite: a concept of Nepalis as a high caste Hindu hill people that justified the exclusion of the indigenous: „non-Hindu ethnic peoples in Nepal had been subjected to a deliberate policy of religious and cultural suppression that converted cultures into castes, assigned each a place in a ranked rituo-political system, and aimed to make people who hailed from non- Brahminical cultures and histories into loyal subjects of the Hindu nation-state.‟ 31 In Nepal a liberal discourse, combining ideas of democracy, rights and development, has become hegemonic as a result of the priorities and resources of international agencies and the willing cooption of national elites who have benefitted from an association with it, through access to funds and careers. The ideologies and institutions of development came to be understood as the definition of modernity 32 even though these were created entirely upon the basis of elite understandings of what a Nepali was and should be: „Instead of building on the traditions and knowledge of the villagers in Nepal, the education they received taught them that the places they came from were ignorant and dirty. Their culture, their religious beliefs, and their ways of using the land apparently were what prevented them from entering the bright, shiny modern world, not the reality that in that world there was not enough – enough opportunities, enough resources – to go around. They were taught that their poverty was the result of who they were and 27 Personal interview, Gopal Dahit, Kathmandu, August 2008. 28 Chhetri 2005. 29 Personal interview, Gopal Dahit, Kathmandu, August 2008. 30 Cheria, Edwin, Kandangwa and Upadhyaya 2005. 31 Leve 2007. 32 Pigg 1996: 160-201; Pigg 1992: 491-513. 6 where they came from – things they could not change - not the result of the deep inequities in the world they hoped to join.‟ 33 For indigenous people, the conflation of this modernising agenda of rights and development with a Nepali culture defined by and in the image of elites created a pressure that actively served to erode indigenous culture. 34 The process of democratisation after 1990 was driven by these liberal values but singularly failed to address any of the substantive issues of poverty, social exclusion, or the violence implicit in many economic relations. Whilst supported by a broad mass of the people, the 1990 movement was led by traditional elites who saw democracy in terms of competitive elections, rather than a challenging of the narrow ethnic and caste base of economic and political power. With the onset of democracy local elites learnt to run political parties in their areas as machines of patronage and in many areas the rich and powerful were able to ensure that their chosen candidates won elections. Electoral democracy changed very little in terms of who represented the people of Bardiya. Non Tharu elites used the institutions of political parties, networks of patronage, and thuggery to win seats in the new democratic parliament. The fraction of civil servants coming from the most powerful caste and ethnic groups increased from the 1980s to the end of the 20 th century, 35 demonstrating that far from addressing issues of social exclusion, the new dispensation that followed the arrival of democracy actually worsened it. At the start of the 21 st century the Brahmin and Chhetri castes, which constitute some 30% of the population of Nepal made up 87% of civil service staff. 36 Because the liberal principles on which the democratic state was founded did not challenge the extreme inequalities that existed, indigenous people and others remained excluded. This issue reflects a deeper fault line in the global human rights project that from its inception elevated individual rights over group rights, leading to the neglect of indigenous peoples that Falk has called a „normative blindness‟. 37 This was reflected in the assimilationist policies that post-1990 Nepali Governments attempted. In both the provinces and the capital the most lucrative jobs lay in foreign development agencies and the national NGOs they supported. Government, which remained substantially corrupt at all levels, 38 could best access funds by articulating the development discourse in its dealings with foreign donors. As a result significant amounts of donor aid were swallowed by elites who had learned the language of development and rights, and rather little reached rural areas, 39 ironically serving to increase the urban-rural economic divide. It was the inability to tackle the fundamental issues affecting many Nepalis, notably exclusion, poverty and uneven development that led to the success of the Maoist People‟s War. Conflict and transition In 1996 a small party from among Nepal‟s fractious Marxist left, the Communist Party of Nepal (Maoist) [CPN-M], declared a „People‟s War‟ against the newly democratic regime. The 33 Armbrecht 2009, 163, discussing a Janajati group in the hills. 34 Pigg 1996. 35 Thapa and Sijapati 2003. 36 Battachan 2008. 37 Falk 1981. 38 Upadhay 2004. 39 Upadhay 2004: According to the report of the Office of Auditor General (2002/3), a total of NRs71.22 billion (nearly one billion in US dollar terms) from various donors has not been accounted for in the annual budgets of the government. 7 insurgency grew rapidly from its initial base in the hills of the impoverished Mid-west with the Maoists conducting military operations throughout the country. They propounded a politics that explicitly encompassed an end to exclusion on the basis of ethnicity, caste and gender and as a result a significant fraction of their cadres were drawn from marginalised groups. 40 The Maoist insurgency began in those areas, notably the poorest, where the state was largely absent and as a result the conflict was fought almost exclusively in rural areas, in both hills and plains, and rural populations became the victims of both sides. By the later years of the insurgency the CPN-M controlled perhaps 80% of the territory of Nepal, with only the headquarters of the 75 districts and major towns under Government control. Because of the ethnic profile of the insurgent forces, many victims belonged to indigenous minorities, in particular where ethnic groups, like the Tharu, were perceived as being generally sympathetic to the insurgency and targeted by the state as a result. One favoured tactic of state forces was to arrest and extra-judicially kill those they suspected of being close to the Maoists. In 2003 Nepal was responsible for a greater number of cases of disappearance reported to the UN‟s Working Group on Enforced Disappearances than any other state. 41 Whilst disappearances 42 were also perpetrated by the Maoists, the vast majority were the responsibility of the forces of the state. The district most affected by disappearances was Bardiya, where more than 250 persons remain unaccounted for, 43 80% of these Tharu, who constitute 52% of the district population. The conflict came to a dramatic end in April 2006, with a second „People‟s Movement‟ uniting the Maoists and the constitutional parties against a king who had again seized absolute power. The conflict left a legacy of some 15,000 dead 44 and more than 1,300 unaccounted for nationally. 45 As part of an ongoing peace process the monarchy has been abolished, a republic declared and following elections to a constituent assembly in 2008 the Maoists are now the largest party in the legislature. The Maoist-led Government that emerged after elections showed no enthusiasm in creating mechanisms of transitional justice despite commitments made in the documents of the peace process. 46 This is due to both a general blocking of legislation that has characterised the politics of the post-election period, and a suspicion among all leading political parties of any process that threatens the prosecution of those who waged the war. As such, the post-conflict debate around transitional justice has been between civil society, led by human rights agencies, and a Government that appears to have little interest. Both international and local human rights agencies have focussed many of their initiatives on issues of transitional justice, and these will be reviewed here in the light of the power dynamics between human rights workers and victims and with reference to Tharu victims in Bardiya. 40 Hangen 2007. 41 Human Rights Watch 2004. 42 According to the definitions of international human rights law only forces linked to a state can perpetrate disappearance (UN Convention on Enforced Disappearance, 2004), whilst arrest and resulting disappearance by a non-state actor, such as the CPN-M, is referred to as abduction. Here, disappearance will be assumed to refer to cases perpetrated by both parties to the conflict in Nepal. 43 ICRC, 2008. 44 INSEC 2007. 45 ICRC, 2008. 46 Government of Nepal 2006. 8 Impact of the conflict The history of dispossession among the Tharu of Bardiya made them receptive to Maoist commitments to ethnic autonomy and land reform and, as a result, the CPN-M found a pool of support in the Tharu community. In districts like Bardiya, where the greatest issue facing the population was that of land and landlessness, as the CPN-M gained effective control of rural areas they also tried to be seen to be addressing such issues. Landlords were targeted, and often forced to flee their lands which were then redistributed to others. However, the conflict took its toll on both individual Tharu farmers and on the Tharu as a community, when the state responded to Maoist success in the district. The Tharu in Bardiya believe that the authorities were unable to discriminate between the Tharu land rights movement and the Maoist insurgency: 47 many of the Tharu people now missing had no connection with the CPN-M. 48 Others taken were community leaders, teachers and activists. However, it appears that the principle reason for the Tharu being targeted by state security forces in Bardiya was as an extension of the struggle over land. From November 2001 the Royal Nepal Army (RNA) was introduced into the conflict against the CPN-M following the failure of the police, along with anti- terrorist legislation that led to a dramatic deterioration in the security situation in Bardiya. Thousands were arrested in Bardiya at this time 49 and disappearances escalated. The greatest number of disappearances occurred following the appointment of a local landowner, from a migrant high caste hill family, to a RNA command position: „His grandfather and father were like kings in this district from a very long time back. They used to pick up any woman they liked from the Tharu village and rape them, entrap Tharu people in their debt [...] If they couldn‟t pay, they had to work as bonded labourers. [the commander] was the son of those feudatory princes and since his childhood his thinking was negative concerning the Tharu community.‟ 50 Methodology of the study The research agenda is driven by the desire to understand victims‟ goals for Nepal‟s transition and compare these with the aims articulated by those driving discussion of transitional justice in Nepal. The research design was therefore developed on a participatory basis with an association of families of the disappeared in Bardiya, the Conflict Victims‟ Committee (CVC). CVC is the largest and oldest association of families of the disappeared in Nepal, having been founded in 2007 by a schoolteacher whose father was disappeared by the state, and claiming the membership of over 200 families. The engagement with family associations helped to build an ethical relationship between the researcher and the researched. 51 The sampling frame used for the study is a list, drawn up by the International Committee of the Red Cross (ICRC), of 241 persons missing as a result of the conflict in Bardiya and published at the start of data collection (ICRC, 2008). A random selection was made from the list to select subjects for interview: of the 31 families met, 28 were Tharu. This represents victims of both sides, although 96% of disappearances in Bardiya were state perpetrated. 52 47 OHCHR 2008. 48 ibid. 49 ibid. 50 Personal interview, Tharu CPN-M leader, Bardiya, July 2008. 51 Robins, 2009. 52 CVC, Bardiya, 2007: personal communication. 9 Subjects were interviewed in their homes as a family group, using a semi-structured approach, developed with CVC leaders. Additionally, CVC selected focus group participants allowing peer groups to be constructed. These included Tharu women and wives of the disappeared. Disappearances had occurred between 12 and 2 years prior to the research, with the average time passed being 5 years. Whilst the methodology is qualitative, the sampling approach allows quantitative statements to be made. The methodology and results of this study are described in detail elsewhere. 53 Interviews were also made with the leadership of CVC, as well as with Tharu intellectuals, local authorities and staff of human rights NGOs in Bardiya, the regional centre and Kathmandu. Research was conducted over a six month period in 2008, some 2 years after the end of the conflict. Victims and the rights discourse Victim priorities of transition When asked about their understanding of human rights most victim families in Bardiya believed that „human rights‟ were a group of NGOs, responding with comments such as: „human rights have come to see us a few times, but have done nothing‟. They were then asked about their specific understanding of their human rights: 'I don’t know about any rights. I just heard that it means n obody should kill human beings, that it‟s a crime to kill people.' 54 „Sometimes I think that when they took our people, they should not have killed them, they have the right to live. […] It is treating them like beasts to kill them immediately after the arrest. They treated our people like dogs. But I don‟t know exactly what rights are.‟ 55 No family met in Bardiya, other than the leader of the victims‟ association, was able to show significant understanding of what human rights are. The data of this study of families of the disappeared in Bardiya 56 indicate that families‟ priorities are for the truth about the fate of loved ones and to retrieve bodies, and economic support so that basic needs for food, healthcare and children‟s education could be met: large majorities prioritised both issues. Justice was mentioned as a priority by only 7% of families in Bardiya. Whilst victims would welcome retributive justice, this is not their priority. Victims have little understanding of rights and articulate needs. Whilst many agencies and donors are devoting funds and programmes to transitional justice in Nepal, rather few efforts have been made to understand what victims want from transition. One study of conflict victims, using largely quantitative methods, has been published by the International Centre for Transitional Justice, and Advocacy Forum, 57 one of Nepal‟s leading national human rights agencies. Most of the report‟s content is concerned with attitudes towards prosecutorial justice and the proposal of a Truth and Reconciliation Commission, while 53 Robins 2009; ICRC 2009. 54 Personal interview, brother of missing Tharu man, Bardiya, August 2008. 55 Personal interview, focus group participant, Bardiya, August 2008. 56 ICRC 2009. 57 ICTJ (International Centre for Transitional Justice) and Advocacy Forum 2008. 10 the survey confirmed that the priorities of victims and their families were: compensation, education, basic needs, such as food, housing, clothing, health and medical facilities, employment and the whereabouts of the disappeared: a mere 3% of those questioned prioritised the punishing of perpetrators. This strongly suggests that victims and their families prioritise basic needs over legal process, and yet the work of those agencies who commissioned the report remains dominated by a judicial agenda (see below). There are additional questions about the sampling and methodology of the report, 58 not least the apparent underrepresentation of the indigenous and of women among those surveyed. Victim emphasis on social and economic needs, rather than the judicial agenda of civil society has been remarked on elsewhere. 59 The analysis here will try to understand why there remains such a gap between the agendas of human rights professionals and the victims themselves in terms of the priorities of Nepal‟s transitional process. Legalism of the rights community It has been observed that the dominance of legalism in transitional justice, in both scholarship and practice has led to a „thin‟ transitional justice that is institutionalised and driven by legal processes 60 that has little relevance for those most affected by violations. The legalist approach is prevalent in Nepal: agencies both national and international advocating for action in response to violations committed during the conflict give primacy to judicial mechanisms, and advocacy has centred on ending impunity, rather than defining justice more broadly. A study of recent publications of Nepali human rights agencies concerning the transition confirm this emphasis: in one 61 the eight “key recommendations” all revolve around prosecution, criminalisation and ending impunity; of the 10 recommendations in a second, 62 whilst some engage with the mechanics of preventing disappearance, most concern prosecutions and none concern the families of those who have disappeared. Both documents understand justice in a narrow prosecutorial way; they are analyses that are perpetrator and violation centred, rather than victim and needs centred. Non-prosecutorial processes, such as the proposed TRC, are seen as a way to name and thus prosecute perpetrators, with other roles considered secondary: „AF [Advocacy Forum] strongly advocates for a Truth and Reconciliation Commission to establish the actual truth and thereby identify and prosecute the perpetrators, provide reparations to victims and create conducive environment for reconciliation in order to provide justice for the victims, end the culture of impunity and reinforce the rule of law.‟ 63 This represents an international trend in approaches to transition, what might be called the judicialisation of transition, in which an „international justice project‟ is privileged over the goals of those most affected by the events of the conflict and indeed the broader needs of the nation. A senior worker at a UN agency in Kathmandu reported that whilst he could understand the perception that victims were being exploited by human rights workers, his agenda was not driven by that of victims in Nepal: his role was „to see perpetrators sent to prison‟. When a senior national human rights agency worker in Kathmandu was asked about the continuing legal emphasis of his work despite victims‟ expressed needs, he replied that „sometimes simple 58 Pasipanodya 2008; Robins 2008. 59 Pasipanodya 2008; Aguirre and Pietropaoli 2008. 60 McEvoy and McGregor 2008. 61 Human Rights Watch and Advocacy Forum 2008, 7-8. 62 INSEC 2008. 63 Advocacy Forum 2007, 1. 11 people do not know what they should want.‟ 64 The rights agenda is being used as a tool to deny agency to victims. Here, we will consider the legalism of those leading advocacy for transitional justice in Nepal and compare their primarily judicial agenda with that of the victims of Bardiya. The law is an abstract concept to most Tharu and, whilst they have been its victims for as long as they have had contact with the Nepali state, few can conceive of it as something that could have relevance in their lives: „The uneducated people don‟t know what rights mean and they don‟t know whether law exists or not. They don‟t know what provisions there are in law. Some of these people even think that the law is for the sake of rich people.‟ 65 Indeed, around one third of victims believe that it is the role of human rights agencies to deliver justice. 66 Confusion over the law was further emphasized when families were asked who they most sought prosecuted: half of families mentioned local informers, who they felt were most responsible for the disappearance, apparently unaware that they are unlikely to have committed a criminal offence. This suggests that what is required in affected communities is not only a formal judicial process, but also something that can bring together members of communities who are divided by the violations of the conflict: a community based process that can address the grievances of victims and promote reconciliation. The principal risk for victims of the constant emphasis of prosecutions is the marginalisation of basic needs, and the diversion of resources of all types to the judicial agenda. Victim families see justice as being much broader than prosecution: almost half see justice as compensation, truth or acknowledgment, rather than prosecution alone. 67 Almost one third would accept an amnesty for perpetrators, if this allowed the truth about disappearance to emerge, or permitted prosecution of those with greatest responsibility. 68 The leader of the Bardiya Association is frustrated at the failure of the victims‟ agenda and that of rights agencies to coincide: justice (in all its forms) is perceived by many victims as something that can only be sought by those whose basic needs are met: „For instance, [an HR agency] works in providing legal support. In the course of it, they frequently invite victims for interactions. The victims are tired of taking part in these meetings; they complain that they cannot participate in meetings, abandoning their work, since they get nothing to eat in the evening if they do not work in the day. But [the agency] does not have any programs to support the livelihoods of the people. [...] To me, it seems that if we could make [the wife of a disappeared man] earn her food and clothes she would go to Gulariya [district HQ] to chant slogans. If she does not have food to eat, she will have to confine herself to the struggle to feed herself.‟ 69 Not only are basic needs a priority, but their satisfaction is seen as a prerequisite to victims being able to campaign for justice. 64 Personal interview with senior human rights agency worker, Kathmandu, September 2008. 65 Personal interview with focus group participant, Bardiya, August 2008. 66 ICTJ (International Centre for Transitional Justice) and Advocacy Forum 2008. 67 Robins, 2009. 68 ibid. 69 Personal interview with leader of CVC Bardiya, Kathmandu September 2008, discussing the typical female relative of the disappeared. 12 This legal lens of human rights workers superimposes upon the complexity of post- conflict Nepal a single dominant approach to transition that claims unique importance to the society as a whole, despite the massive diversity of ways in which the conflict was experienced. It implies that the impact of a conflict born of exclusion, oppression and grossly unequal distributions of power and resources can be addressed largely by a judicial process. More than this it homogenises the many complex and varied demands of victims, arising from their unique experiences of the conflict, into something that can readily be addressed by central institutions rather than through solutions that emerge from victims‟ communities. An extreme example of this legalism has been the efforts of a UN agency and an INGO to offer legal advice to landlords displaced from Bardiya, in an effort to regain their property following CPN-M seizure and redistribution of their land. This appears to local people as simply a political attempt on behalf of elites to return Nepal to a status quo that has been challenged irrevocably by the conflict. The definition of a violation of rights implicitly privileges particular forms of violence over others. The violence of the conflict that led to killings and disappearance are violations according to those representing the human rights discourse in contemporary Nepal, while the violence of social and economic exclusion and exploitation are not: efforts by the CPN-M to redress unequal property relations through land redistribution are considered violations themselves. Human rights has no theory of violence, 70 but as a state-centred discourse sanctions violence that maintains the existing social order. McEvoy describes this as the rights discourse „seeing like a state‟. 71 This is a symptom of a liberal rights discourse that uses a narrow legalism to ignore the politics that underlie situations that are the result of unequal power relations: „legalism [...] incessantly translates wide-ranging political questions into more narrowly framed legal questions.‟ 72 Moreover human rights „sees‟ with the same partial eyes as the state, and when the state is exclusionary it is likely that human rights practice will also be. This is the natural result of a human rights that has: „... a Western centric and top-down focus; it self presents (at least) as apolitical; it includes a capacity to disconnect from the real political and social world of transition [...] and finally it suggests a predominant focus upon retribution as the primary mechanism to achieve accountability‟ 73 The result of this legalism is that „rights work in conjunction with capitalism and serve as a regulatory discourse, at once normalising certain relations of power and co-opting more radical political demands‟. 74 The Tharu of Bardiya see a solution to their problems not in terms of the legal lens applied by rights workers but in terms of something that can put food on their table and ensure their access to land and livelihood in the long term: political demands. Where the state and law have always been servants of elites remote from ordinary people, as in Nepal, transitional justice will require more than the simple application of law to engage with conflict affected communities and to transform the state. This is made explicit when one considers assurances of non-repetition of any violation that are part of the legal right to reparation. 75 In Nepal human rights workers emphasise the reform of the responsible institutions, such as the 70 Goodale and Merry 2007. 71 Scott 1999. 72 Brown and Halley 2002,19. 73 McEvoy and McGregor 2008, 24. 74 Speed 2008, 67. 75 Joinet 1997. 13 army and police, while the victims themselves see the problem as more fundamental and articulate different demands: „We want a Tharu State. [...] There were political reasons behind the conflict. [...] Therefore, politics should solve the problems behind the conflict. For all this, giving an autonomous state to the Tharu people is the best way of solving the problems; they would manage their affairs on their own.‟ 76 Cultural and social issues For many families of the disappeared the most extreme impacts of violations are cultural and social, as power relations within families are skewed and the attitude of the community altered by the fact of disappearance. Most notably for the wives of the disappeared problems arise because they do not see themselves as widows, and continue to wear the visible signs of marriage, such as red sindhur powder in the hair and bangles. Within the traditional joint family there are power relationships, in which young women are dependent for their status on their husband. If he disappears the wife is perceived as having an ambiguous connection to the family, who brings no income to the household, and who may be seeking to elope with another man and bring shame on the family. My in-laws call me very bad things such as prostitute, witch, widow, etc in front of my children when they see me around. (Focus group participant, Katarniya, Bardiya.) The result of this often extreme stigmatisation is that such women will be treated as a servant, denied food and considered with suspicion. Leaving the family will be impossible in the absence of economic independence, and will often demand leaving children behind. In the community, stigma can arise from a perceived association to the Maoists, which the community punish by excluding the family of the disappeared: People don‟t let us drink or bring water from their hand pump. Other kids and people beat my children when I am not in the house. (Wife of missing man, Bardiya.) The issues that lead to women being stigmatised in the family can also lead to problems in the community. The ambiguity over a women‟s marital status and her persistence in wearing the symbols of marriage create the impression that the wives of the Missing are somehow predatory in their search for a new husband. Women report being called whores, and being sexually harassed. These impacts are a direct result of disappearance in the social world in which families of the disappeared live, arising as a result of power relations within families and communities. The rights discourse has little to say about such issues, and in post-conflict Nepal these impacts are invisible outside the impacted communities; agencies working on transitional justice issues have never acknowledged these impacts and remain largely unaware of them. Social and economic rights and victim needs „I have a 6-year-old daughter who is disabled - she was born four days after the disappearance. The security forces took my husband when I started to feel labour pain. [...] I don‟t have money to cure her. As I don‟t have enough to eat, how can I meet the expenses for her treatment?‟ 77 76 Personal interview with leader of CVC Bardiya, Kathmandu September 2008. 77 Personal interview with focus group participant, Bardiya, August 2008. 14 In studies to date 78 and the data of this research, 79 victims of the conflict prioritise livelihoods and the economic well-being of their families. It has been observed that in transitional justice advocacy in Nepal, despite the clear evidence that they are a priority for victims, social and economic rights have taken second place to civil and political rights. In principle, there is „interdependence and indivisibility‟ 80 of all rights, but in both the global rights discourse and in praxis (in Nepal and elsewhere), social, economic and cultural rights are far less emphasised. To this author‟s knowledge, no documents or strategies of advocacy have emerged from the leading Nepali human rights agencies advocating for social and economic rights; potential compensation and economic support for victims is always framed in terms of a legally based „right to reparation‟, essentially reframing the issue as a civil/political right. That social and economic rights are secondary has been implicitly acknowledged, in principle in recognition of developing states‟ challenges in realising such rights, through the concept of „progressive realisation‟ 81 of social and economic rights. In transitional justice, the lack of emphasis globally on social and economic rights has been acknowledged at the highest level: „By reaching beyond its criminal law-rooted mechanisms to achieve social justice, transitional justice could contribute to expand our traditional and reductive understanding of “justice” by rendering it its full meaning.‟ 82 The language of need is that used by most victims met in this study, and their daily experience confronts them with unmet needs, very often the most basic; the language of rights is an alien one. In the long term, sustainable solutions to the livelihood deficit seen among both Tharu conflict victims and many other sections of Nepal‟s population will involve both economic development and the confrontation of the structural inequalities in terms of social and economic exclusion. For the Tharu of Bardiya this demands land reform and mechanisms to ensure that they will never again have their land stolen from them. In contemporary Nepal, the claiming of social and economic rights amounts to a challenge to the social, economic and political order of the pre-transition (i.e. pre-2006) state. Whilst in rhetoric this is accepted at the political level, civil society generally and human rights agencies in particular have proved themselves unable or unwilling to articulate the economic and social needs of victims and to challenge entrenched hierarchies that ensure most remain poor. The retributive roots of transitional justice and narrow agenda of its practitioners continue to prevent the emergence of a practice that can deliver a broader justice after conflict that includes addressing the social injustice that led to conflict. Transitional Justice in an unequal society Whilst the impact of the violations that most defined Nepal‟s conflict, such as disappearances, fell largely upon the rural and the disempowered, the response to those violations is being shaped by others. In the years since the end of armed conflict the authorities have failed to create mechanisms of transitional justice 83 and international and national human rights agencies in the capital are attempting to fashion a transitional justice agenda. 78 Ibid. 79 Robins 2009. 80 e.g. UN 1998. 81 International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights 1966, Article 2. 82 Arbour 2007, 8. 83 After this research was made, the Government made a payment of „relief‟ of 100,000 rupees (a little over $1,300) to most families of the disappeared. 15 Human rights agencies, particularly at the senior level, are dominated by members of elites. The indigenous and dalits are excluded from jobs with both national and international rights agencies as they are from many other sectors, as a result of low educational achievement and discrimination. There are no dalits in leadership positions in civil society 84 and few from indigenous communities. Whilst agencies have made efforts at more inclusive staffing policies in recent years, those defining the transitional justice agenda are remote from most victims in terms of class, ethnicity, caste, education, language and geography. Lawoti 85 has studied the approaches to inclusion of Arnstein and Cornwall 86 in the Nepali context, defining modes of inclusion as: manipulation, cooptation, instrumental, consultative and transformative, with only the latter seeking to change the unequal structures that create exclusion. One can try to understand the relationship between rights agencies and victims in Bardiya on these terms. Efforts at consultation are well represented by the one published effort at consultation that sought to understand victims‟ views of transition, a largely quantitative survey of victims. 87 This study tells us something of the priorities of those who prepared the survey, dominated as it is by questions about prosecutions and a TRC, and only little about the fact that the priorities of victims are largely social and economic 88 . This is consultation but not on the terms of those being consulted, and thus fails to even satisfy Lawoti‟s definition of instrumental inclusion; such a survey aims to lend legitimacy to an agenda that has not changed in response to victims‟ views and is best described as cooptation. One remarkable phenomenon was when human rights NGOs chose to invite victims to meetings in Kathmandu. Such meetings typically operated at a level entirely beyond the typical Bardiya villager: they would be conducted in English or Nepali and would typically be discussing international precedents in transitional justice and the implications for Nepal. The role of the victim was to speak about his or her suffering when requested and be listened to in a respectful silence. Often a victim would break down in tears, demonstrating how highly disturbing the exercise was for them, but they would be otherwise ignored during the meeting. This appears to represent the fetishisation or commodification of victims: their role was symbolic, to acknowledge both their existence and their supposed primacy in the ongoing discussion, but not to permit them to actually impinge on agendas being set by others. This is a mode of inclusion best described as manipulation: victims, particularly from marginalised communities, are included in such meetings as tokens, but no weight is given to their agenda or to the role their indigenousness played in their becoming victims. This permits the rights agencies to ignore the extent to which ethnicity and caste impact on victimhood, and exclude such topics from the transitional agenda. Beyond such contacts the interface between the global rights discourse and a Tharu victim in Bardiya is tenuous, being made through a layered structure of foreign donors, national NGO workers at several levels, and activist victims. Such contact as there is occurs between victims or their representatives, such as those from CVC, and regional or district agency offices who may travel to the villages. The activities of the agencies in turn consist largely of training: exercises in the dissemination of the rights discourse to victims and others, including the emphasis on civil and political rights and a judicial approach. In order to benefit from the patronage of agencies, those who seek to represent victims must learn the global rights language, 89 and only those who present an agenda that coincides with the legalist programme of the agencies will benefit from 84 Bhattachan, Sunar and Bhattachan (Gauchan) 2007. 85 Lawoti 2009. 86 Arnstein, 1969; Cornwall 2002. 87 ICTJ (International Centre for Transitional Justice) and Advocacy Forum 2008. 88 Robins 2009. 89 Language here is both literal and metaphoric: most Tharu speak Nepali badly if at all. 16 invitations to Kathmandu programmes and potential support for activities. The domestic rights agencies are funded by international donors who have little direct contact with victims and depend upon the agencies themselves for their understanding of victim attitudes, and so those whose agenda does not coincide with such groups are not funded. The almost complete absence of support to CVC, the oldest and largest district victims‟ organisation in the country, appears to confirm this. In interviews with the leader of the Bardiya Family Association, the nature of the interaction between victims‟ representatives and those representing the human rights discourse was made clear. The Family Association was unable to forge substantial relations with donors: The donors won‟t trust organisations in Bardiya and the big organisations in Kathmandu are backed by the donors but they fail in Bardiya. [...] I and the members represent the victims and we are in favour of bringing programmes if donors show up. But the big organizations work in accordance with the interests of donors. On the other hand, we set our programs on the basis of ground realities but the donors don‟t give money to us.‟ 90 The one embassy donor CVC had found withdrew their funding to that of a national victims‟ organisation being set up by one of the leading human rights agencies, to the bewilderment of the existing association. Ultimately, CVC was told that if it sought to join the national network it would have to change its remit from representing families of the disappeared to representing all victims of the conflict, otherwise it would receive no funding. As a result, the entire basis of the association was changed due to the use of financial pressure by those with funds in the capital. This demonstrates that whilst rights agencies in Nepal are working to mobilise victims, an apparent prerequisite to empower victims‟ groups, they are being mobilised on terms set by elites rather than by victims themselves. A constant complaint of the CVC president was that the human rights agencies are led by members of elites from Kathmandu, who have no understanding of the Tharu of Bardiya or their needs, and spend most of their funds in the capital, rather than where victims are. Victim families are aware that large sums are spent on human rights work, much of it paying salaries that are considered enormous by their standards, to both foreigners and Nepalese. Given that their demands are primarily economic it is inevitable that they also compare their own poverty with the apparent wealth of the human rights industry in their country. The class and caste composition of the human rights agencies is largely elite; there are no Tharu in the Kathmandu office of any large rights agency and even in Tharu majority areas, such as Bardiya, almost all agency staff are non-Tharu and non Tharu speaking. Meetings with victims in rural Bardiya run by one of the most prominent Nepali human rights agencies were attended as part of this research. The agency staffer was not Tharu and as a result many of the victims attending understood rather little. No effort was made to ask victims about their needs, the priorities were to articulate an agenda emphasising prosecution of perpetrators, and to discuss the details of a proposed Truth and Reconciliation Committee, where the agency was opposing Government proposals to enshrine amnesty. The exercise was one of promoting an agenda originating with elites in the capital over that of the victims of the conflict. In Bardiya the rights agencies are perceived as not seeking to address the structural issues that caused the conflict, notably that of exclusion: „Since the human rights of the people have been violated on a caste basis, I believe that human rights issues should be raised on a caste basis as well. They have been trying to 90 Personal interview with leader of CVC Bardiya, Kathmandu September 2008. 17 make us backward showing that we are not educated people and we could not speak English. [...] They want us to be merely beneficiaries. This is Brahministic thinking, traditional thinking as practiced by the petty kings in the past. [HR agency leader] represents those people having a similar mind-set [...] we were not [just] backward; we were forced to remain backward.‟ 91 Here a direct connection is made between high caste leadership of transitional justice advocacy and traditional high caste exclusion of others. Because those leading the transitional justice effort in civil society are themselves from the very elites who benefitted from social stratification and inequality, these social relations are intrinsic to the relationship between the indigenous victims in Bardiya and the representatives of the global rights discourse. Additionally, the explicit political alignment of many rights workers impacts on their attitudes and activities. Most human rights workers and agencies are associated formally or otherwise with a party 92 that participated in Governments that fought the Maoist insurgency, and whose members were targeted by the Maoists during the insurgency. This gives additional reason for the Tharu of Bardiya to believe that such people have no commitment to the fundamental changes in Nepali society that the post-conflict dispensation is committed to. Conclusions: Toward a victim-centred transitional justice Ignatieff has written that „Human rights matter because they help people to help themselves. They protect their agency.‟ 93 This study suggests that in a post-conflict transition in an unequal society the human rights discourse can be used to do just the opposite; that indigenous victims are denied agency by elites using the discourse of human rights. For the indigenous villagers of rural Nepal who became the victims of conflict human rights is a discourse that comes „from above‟ and is largely disseminated by members of elites who have traditionally benefited from the historic exclusion of the indigenous (and others). As a result of the narrowness of the transitional justice agenda that emerges, its emancipatory potential is highly constrained: it seeks to address the violations of the conflict, but defines these in a limited way and seeks remedies that emerge from a legalistic analysis. It makes no effort to address the unequal social relations that led to the conflict, and more than this the human rights discourse itself appears to act to maintain and enforce the most fundamental power relations within Nepali society. This appears to confirm what has been written about the limits of rights as an instrument of emancipation in unequal societies: „… [rights] may become ... a regulatory discourse, a means of obstructing or co-opting more radical political demands [...] The point is that rights converge with powers of social stratification and lines of social demarcation in ways that extend as often as attenuate these powers and lines.‟ 94 91 Personal interview with leader of CVC Bardiya, Kathmandu September 2008. 92 Communist Party of Nepal – Unified Marxist Leninist (UML); indeed, one of the most important national agencies INSEC (Informal Sector Service Centre) is run by someone who stood in early 2009 for the position of President of UML. 93 Ignatieff 2001, 57. 94 Brown 1995, 98. 18 The first priority for transitional process in Nepal to challenge such constraints is by seeking to broaden it beyond the legalistic to include those elements, notably the social and economic, which challenge the social injustice that led to conflict. To describe the interaction of the global human rights discourse with the Tharu victims of Bardiya as a simple binary or dialectical relationship between the global and the local is to simplify the situation. In practice we see that human rights are constructed through a complex and layered process. The global discourse is instantiated through the actions of international actors and national human rights agencies working in the capital, while contact with the victims themselves is mediated by staff in regional offices and representatives of victims. In this way the human rights discourse filters down to victims who know nothing of rights and articulate their demands in terms of needs, which are translated into rights-based language for the consumption of those higher up the chain. In this way, the true desires of victims are sublimated into a rights-centred discourse regardless of how relevant it may be to what is actually being articulated. This study supports the contention that relationships between those who represent the human rights discourse in the developing world and excluded victims of violations have embedded within them power relations of a colonial character: 95 elites who have access to the discourse import skewed power relations into the practice of human rights. This both dismisses communities of rural victims as a site of production of human rights, in favour of concepts imported from the capital and ultimately from the West, and renders certain forms of violence, notably that inherent in local power relations, invisible to the discourse. This is done by steering funds and granting access to elites (in civil society and in Government) only to those who have internalised the legalism of the rights discourse. Challenging elite control of the transitional discussion in Government and civil society demands replacing tokenistic attitudes to the incorporation of victim perspectives with genuine participation. Confining transitional justice to a politics of rights under liberal political institutions in which existing power relationships are enshrined, ties any process to the system that produced those power relations. Systems of domination, that include iniquitous property relations and the systematic exclusion of those most impacted both by inequality and conflict (such as the indigenous), must be challenged in any transitional process by recognising the agency of those victimised and challenging power structures that embody the relations that led to conflict. „Examining rights from the perspective of actual struggles makes it possible for analysis to transcend accepted normative parameters of human rights debates, question conceptual categories and expand the range of claims that are validated as rights:‟ 96 Expanding the range of claims made means challenging the legalism of elites, such that social and economic needs of victims, and others, can be considered valid, rights-based demands of transitional justice. Beginning with deeper consultation with affected communities, rights agencies should be working to build capabilities to enable indigenous victims to take part as equals in decision making. If those who purport to represent victims are unable to do this, then it is highly unlikely that the transitional process for which they are advocating will be at all inclusive. Mobilisation of victims must be supported on the basis of their own agendas and not subject to their sanctioning by local and international elites. As a result of the power relations that permeate the practice of human rights in a highly unequal society such as Nepal it is 95 Goodale and Merry 2007. 96 Nyamu-Musembi 2005, 31. 19 problematic to consider the rights discourse as the sole legitimate driver of transitional justice. Whilst human rights remains a tool of strategy and mobilisation for oppressed groups seeking justice after conflict, victims‟ organisations offer an alternative route, in which victims themselves have full agency, free of agendas set by elites and less constrained by traditional power relations to use the language of rights or not. Such locally-grown, „non-human rights‟ efforts to both address the issues arising from conflict and to fight for political and social change in the system that led to conflict can provide unique input to create transitional justice process that can give space to the agendas of victims. 20 References Abu-Nimer, Mohammed. 2001. Reconciliation, justice, and coexistence: Theory and practice. Maryland: Lexington. Advocacy Forum. 2007. Transitional Justice: Advocacy Forum newsletter, September – October 2007. Kathmandu: Advocacy Forum. Aguirre, Daniel and Irene Pietropaoli. 2008. Gender equality, development and transitional justice: The case of Nepal. The International Journal of Transitional Justice 2:1-22. Arbour, Louise. 2007. Economic and social justice for societies in transition. NYU Journal of International law and politics 40(1):1-27. Armbrecht, Ann. 2009. Thin places: A pilgrimage home. New York: Columbia University Press. Arnstein, Sherry R. 1969. A Ladder of Citizen Participation. JAIP 35 (4): 216-224. Battachan, Krishna B.2008. Indigenous nationalities and minorities of Nepal. Kathmandu: Nepal Federation of Indigenous Nationalities. Bhattachan, Krishna B.,Tej B. Sunar and Yasso Kanti Bhattachan (Gauchan). 2007. Caste based discrimination in Nepal. Delhi: Indian Institute of Dalit Studies (HDS), and Copenhagen: International Dalit Solidarity Network. Bowd, Richard and Alp Ozerdem (eds.). In press. Participatory Research Methodologies in Development and Post Disaster/Conflict Reconstruction. London: Ashgate. Brown, Wendy and Janet Halley. 2002. Introduction. In Brown et al. 2002: 19. Brown, Wendy and Janet Halley, Mark Kelman and Gillian Lester. 2002. Left legalism / left critique. North Carolina :Duke University Press. Brown, Wendy. 1995. States of injury: Power and freedom in late modernity. NJ: Princeton University Press. Cheria, Anita, Edwin Nanda Kumar Kandangwa and Khemraj Upadhyaya. 2005. Liberation is not enough: The Kamaiya movement in Nepal. Kathmandu: ActionAid Nepal. Chhetri, Ram, B. 2005. The Plight of the Tharu Kamaiyas of Nepal: A Review of Social Economic and Political Facets. Occasional Papers in Sociology and Anthropology, Central Department of Sociology and Anthropology, Tribhuvan University: Kathmandu. Conway, Dennis, Keshav. Bhattarai and Nanda. R. Shrestha. 2000. Population–environment relations at the forested frontier of Nepal: Tharu and Pahari survival strategies in Bardiya. Applied Geography 20: 221–242. Cornwall, Andrea. 2002. Locating citizen participation. IDS Bulletin 33 (2): 49 – 58. Danida. 2004. Social institutions of the Tharu. Kathmandu: Danida. de Haan, Arjan. 1998. Social Exclusion: Enriching the Understanding of Deprivation, London: DFID. Duschinski, Haley. 2008. Try out participatory justice, Combat Law 7(4). (Available online at: www.combatlaw.org/print.php?article_id=1181&issue_id=41) Falk, Richard. 1981. Human rights and state sovereignty. New York: Holmes and Meier. 21 Goodale, Mark and Sally A. Merry. 2007. The practice of human rights: Tracking law between the global and the local. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Goodale, Mark. 2007. Locating rights, envisioning law between the global and the local. In Goodale 2007: 1-38. Government of Nepal. 2006. Comprehensive Peace Agreement. Kathmandu: Govt. Of Nepal. Guneratne, Arjun. 2004. Many Tongues, One People: The Making of Tharu Identity in Nepal. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. Hangen, Susuan. 2007. Creating a new Nepal: The ethnic dimension: Policy Studies 34. Washington: East-West Centre. Höfer. Andras. 2004. The Caste Hierarchy and the State in Nepal - A Study of the Muluki Ain of 1854. Kathmandu: Himal Books. Human Rights Watch and Advocacy Forum. 2008. Waiting for justice: Unpunished crimes from Nepal’s armed conflict, Kathmandu: HRW and AF. Human Rights Watch. 2004. Between a rock and a hard place: Civilians Struggle to Survive in Nepal’s Civil War. Washington: Human Rights Watch. ICRC (International Committee of the Red Cross). 2008. Missing persons in Nepal: The right to know. Kathmandu: ICRC. ICRC (International Committee of the Red Cross). 2009. An assessment of the needs of the families of the Missing in Nepal, Kathmandu: ICRC. ICTJ (International Centre for Transitional Justice) and Advocacy Forum. 2008. Nepali Voices: perceptions of Truth, Justice, Reparations and The Transition in Nepal. Kathmandu: ICTJ / AF, 2008. Ignatieff, Michael. 2001. Human rights as politics and idolatry. NJ: Princeton University Press. INSEC. 2007. Human Rights Yearbook 2007. Kathmandu: INSEC. Available online at: http://www.inseconline.org/YB_Book.php INSEC. 2008 Impaired accountability: State of disappearance in Nepal. Kathmandu: INSEC. Donnelly, Jack. 1984. Cultural Relativism and Universal Human Rights. Human Rights Quarterly 6: 400-419. Joinet, Michael. 1997. Question of the impunity of perpetrators of human rights violations (civil and political. UN/Doc. E/CN.4/Sub.2/1997/20/Rev.1. ?:?. Kabeer, Naila and Ramya Subrahmanian. 2005. Inclusive Citizenship: Meanings and Expressions. London: Zed Books. Kriesberg. Louis. 2001. Changing forms of coexistence. In Abu-Nimer 2001: 47-86. Lawoti, Mahendra. 2009. Dissecting ‘inclusion. The Kathmandu Post, April 3 rd 2009. Leve, Lauren. 2007. „Secularism is a human right!‟: Double binds of Buddhism, democracy, and identity in Nepal. In Goodale and Merry 2007: 78-114. Mani, Rama. 2008. Dilemmas of Expanding Transitional Justice, or Forging the Nexus between Transitional Justice and Development. The International Journal of Transitional Justice. 2: 253 - 265, McEvoy, Kieran and McGregor, Lorna. 2008. Transitional Justice from Below: An agenda for research, policy and praxis. In McEvoy and McGregor. 2008: 1- 14. 22 McEvoy, Kieran and McGregor, Lorna. 2008. Transitional justice from below: Grassroots activism and the struggle for change. Oxford: Hart, 2008. McEvoy, Kieran. 2008. Letting go of legalism: Developing a “thicker” version of transitional justice. In McEvoy and McGregor. 2008: 15-46. Nyamu-Musembi, Celestine. 2005. Toward an actor-oriented perspective on human rights. In Kabeer and Subrahmanian. 2005: 31-49. OHCHR (UN Office of the High Commissioner for Human Rights), 2008. Conflict-related disappearances in Bardiya district. Kathmandu: OHCHR. Orentlicher, Diane. 1991. Settling accounts: The duty to prosecute human rights violations of a prior regime, Yale Law Journal 100: 2537. Orentlicher, Diane. 2007. Settling accounts revisited: Reconciling global norms with local agency. Int. Journal of Transitional Justice, 1: 10-22 Pannikar, Raimundo. 1984. Is the Notion of Human Rights a Western Concept? Cahier, 81: 28- 47. Pasipanodya, Tafadzwa. 2008. A Deeper Justice: Economic and social justice as transitional justice in Nepal. The International Journal of Transitional Justice 2: 378–397. Pigg, Stacey L. 1992. Inventing Social Categories through Place: Social Representations and Development in Nepal. Comparative Studies in Society and History 34(3): 491-513. Pigg, Stacey L. 1996. The Credible and the Credulous: The Question of "Villagers' Beliefs" in Nepal. Cultural Anthropology 11( 2): 160-201; Pollis, Adamantia and Peter Schwab. 1989. Human Rights: A Western construct with limited applicability. In Pollis and Schwab. 1989. Pollis,Adamantia and Peter Schwab. 1989. Human Rights: Cultural and ideological perspectives. New York: Praeger Publishers Inc. Rajagopal, Balakrishnan. 2003. International law from below, Cambridge: CUP. Republic of South Africa. 1999. Truth and Reconciliation Commission Final Report. Pretoria: South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission. Robins, Simon. In press. A participatory approach to ethnographic research with victims of gross human rights violations: Studying families of the disappeared in post-conflict Nepal. In Bowd, and Ozerdem 2009. Robins, Simon. 2009. An assessment of the needs of families of the Missing in Nepal. York: PRDU. Available online at: http://www.simonrobins.com/NepalMissingReport-Robins.pdf Robins, Simon. 2009. Whose voices? Understanding victims' needs in transition. Journal of Human Rights Practice, 1(2): 320. Scott, James C. 1999. Seeing Like a State: How Certain Schemes to Improve the Human Condition Have Failed. New Haven: Yale University Press. Speed, Sharon. 2008. At the crossroads of human rights and anthropology: Toward a critically engaged activist research. American Anthropologist, 108(1): 66 - 76. Stammers, Neil. 1999. Social Movements and the Social Construction of Human Rights. Human Rights Quarterly 21.4: 980-1008. Teitel, Ruti G. 2000. Transitional Justice. Oxford: OUP. 23 Teitel, Ruti G. 2003. Transitional justice genealogy. Harvard Human Rights Journal 16: 69 - 94. Thapa, Deepak and Bandita Sijapati. 2003. A kingdom under siege: Nepal’s Maoist Insurgency, 1996-2003. Kathmandu: The Printhouse. UN. 1966. International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights. ?:?. UN. 1998. Indivisibility and interdependence of human rights stressed by speakers as third committee discussion of human rights matters continues. UN Press Release GA/SHC/3501. ?:?. UNDP. 2004. UNDP Human development Report 2004. Geneva: UNDP. Available online at: http://www.undp.org.np/publication/html/nhdr2004/index.php Upadhay, S.N. 2004. Improving Donor Effectiveness in Combating Corruption Sharing Nepal‟s Experience. Paper prepared for the DAC Development Partnership Forum: Improving Donor Effectiveness in Combating Corruption organised jointly by OECD Development Assistance Committee and Transparency International, 9-10 December 2004. Wilson, Richard A. 1997. Human rights, culture and context: An introduction. In Wilson, 1997. Wilson, Richard A. (ed.) 1997. Human rights, culture and context: Anthropological perspective. London: Pluto Press. work_imdf4hbumvh5pj2pxfyezacbmi ---- Durham Research Online Deposited in DRO: 08 April 2015 Version of attached �le: Accepted Version Peer-review status of attached �le: Peer-reviewed Citation for published item: Turner, C. (2013) 'Deconstructing transitional justice.', Law and critique., 24 (2). pp. 193-209. Further information on publisher's website: http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10978-013-9119-z Publisher's copyright statement: The �nal publication is available at Springer via http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10978-013-9119-z. Additional information: Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-pro�t purposes provided that: • a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • a link is made to the metadata record in DRO • the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Please consult the full DRO policy for further details. Durham University Library, Stockton Road, Durham DH1 3LY, United Kingdom Tel : +44 (0)191 334 3042 | Fax : +44 (0)191 334 2971 http://dro.dur.ac.uk http://www.dur.ac.uk http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10978-013-9119-z http://dro.dur.ac.uk/15047/ http://dro.dur.ac.uk/policies/usepolicy.pdf http://dro.dur.ac.uk 1 Deconstructing Transitional Justice Catherine Turner Transitional Justice Institute University of Ulster Shore Road Newtownabbey BT37 0QB Tel: 028 90 366693 Email: cj.turner@ulster.ac.uk ABSTRACT Transitional justice as a field of inquiry is a relatively new one. Referring to the range of mechanisms used to assist the transition of a state or society from one form of (usually repressive) rule to a more democratic order, transitional justice has become the dominant language in which the move from war to peace is discussed in the early 21 st century. Applying a deconstructive analysis to the question of transitional justice, the paper seeks to interrogate the core assumptions that underlie transitional justice literature in relation to the relationship between law, politics and justice. As a discourse, transitional justice is replete with antinomies or binary oppositions, that of war and peace being the most obvious. Therefore the essentially decsontructible structure of differánce already exists within the concept. By examining the ways in which legal and political narratives are framed and reproduced, the paper seeks to deconstruct the opposition between law and politics on which much of the transitional justice literature rests. The article does not purport to provide a definitive critical analysis of transitional justice but aims to provoke debate and to prompt critical scholars to engage with the themes raised by providing an introductory analysis of some of the core features of a field of inquiry which seems ripe for deconstruction. KEYWORDS Transitional Justice; deconstruction; violence; law; justice; politics mailto:cj.turner@ulster.ac.uk 2 1. Introduction to Transitional Justice Transitional justice as a field of inquiry is a relatively new one. Referring to the range of mechanisms used to assist the transition of a state or society from one form of (usually repressive) rule to a more democratic order, transitional justice has become the dominant language in which the move from war to peace is discussed in the early 21 st century (Bell 2009). From its origins in political science, documenting the efforts of states to deal with the crimes of past governments, such as the military dictatorships in Latin America, transitional justice has taken on the form of a normative framework for dealing with political transformation (IJTJ 2007). Central to this evolution has been a resurgence of the idea of international human rights law and belief in the capacity of law to transcend partisan politics and therefore mediate social change. The rise of transitional justice has been stellar, but it is a field in which theory has failed to keep pace with doctrinal and empirical developments. While there has been significant critical engagement with the requirements of transition, notably but not exclusively from feminist legal scholars, this critique has focused on the need to ensure a more broadly defined and nuanced definition of transitional justice. To date there has been remarkably little theorisation of the concept of transitional justice itself and the way in which this new concept has shaped the way in which we think about law and politics. Applying a deconstructive analysis to the question of transitional justice, the paper seeks to interrogate the core assumptions that underlie transitional justice literature in relation to the relationship between law, politics and justice. A number of features of transitional justice lend themselves particularly well to deconstructive analysis. As a discourse, transitional justice is replete with antinomies or binary oppositions. The most obvious of these are those of war and peace, and also that of peace and justice which characterised early transitional justice debates. However also included within the discourse are the oppositions between democratic and non- democratic, and repressive and transformed, with the distinction between good and evil that this implies. Similarly operating is the distinction between victim and perpetrator that shapes the boundaries of political inclusion and exclusion in transitional contexts. Opposition therefore goes to the very heart of transitional justice discourse and is the foundation upon which theorising has occurred. Therefore the essentially decsontructible structure of differánce already exists within the concept of transitional justice. It is not then surprising that research and advocacy in the field has also tended to rest on binary divisions, for example between procedural and substantive models of law, and the distinction between law and politics per se. However rather than problematising or interrogating these dichotomies, transitional justice scholars to date have tended to speak of law as a means of moving from one to the other. The assumption that appears to underlie much of the theorisation of the role of law in transition is that it is necessary to move from one to the other- from war to peace, for example, or from partisan politics to the rule of law. Also contained within this is an implicit assumption that the move from one to the other is teleologically determined progress (Teitel 2003). By examining the ways in which legal and political narratives are framed and reproduced, the paper seeks to deconstruct the opposition between law and politics on which much of the transitional justice literature rests. The article does not purport to provide a definitive critical analysis of transitional justice. Any one of the 3 themes raised in the article could be the subject of conferences, research papers and books. Rather it aims to provoke debate and to prompt critical scholars to engage with the themes raised by providing an introductory analysis of some of the core features of a field of inquiry which seems ripe for deconstruction. The article is structured around three key moments in the development of transitional justice: the foundation of the disciplinary space; its constitutive exclusions; and the return of that which is excluded (Beardsworth 1996). Section one will explore some of the central features of transitional justice. It will do this by examining it through the lens of transitional justice as a performative force which has shaped the boundaries of how we think about question of justice in the aftermath of conflict. It will consider the way in which transitional justice engages questions of violence, law and politics in transitional contexts and the idea that law can be regarded as playing a role that is distinct from that of politics. Section two seeks to interrogate the underlying assumptions on which the discourse of transitional justice is founded, exploring the idea that law is the means by which justice in transition can be achieved. It will focus in particular on the way in which the boundaries of transitional justice are shaped by the juxtaposition of law with politics and the role that law plays in ensuring the ongoing preservation of the disciplinary space. Section three will focus in more detail on the concept of justice in transition. It will examine some of the divergent priorities of transitional justice and consider these combine to shape an overarching narrative of justice in transition. It will examine the relationship between law and justice that is presented in the transitional justice literature, drawing on the work of Derrida to question the extent to which law is capable of delivering justice. In particular section three will ask whether the exclusionary structure of law itself means that justice is irreducible to law in transitional societies. It will do this in the context of the imposition of regulative ideals and the translation of transcendental ideas into empirical reality. Deconstructive analysis should reveal both the possibilities as well as the dangers of relying on law as a means of achieving justice in transition. For while it is clear that Derrida regards law as necessary, and as a means of pursuing justice, it is equally clear that law cannot in and of itself achieve justice (Derrida 1992). Therefore a balance must be struck when attempting to achieve justice through law. On the one hand law can provide a framework for the pursuit of justice, but on the other it should not be regarded as the same thing as justice. 2. The Performative Force of Transitional Justice a. The emergence of practice Transitional justice as a concept was unheard of in international law prior to the end of the Cold War. While retrospective claims are often made about the genesis of transitional justice in the trials at Nuremberg, the term itself was not applied until the 1990s (Arthur 2009) 4 Efforts at achieving what is now termed transitional justice during the 1970’s and 1980s had been subject to political wrangling, subject to whatever concession on human rights could be secured politically rather than rooted in a normative (let alone international) obligation to pursue a particular course of action (Teitel 2003). Work in the field in the early years consisted primarily of the documentation of efforts that were already being made by states to deal with abusive governments. Dancy describes this phase as the “cataloguing of those structural realities within political transitions that harness the possibilities for victims’ justice” (Dancy 2010, p 356). With the end of the Cold War and the apparent triumph of liberalism, a new found confidence allowed normative conclusions to be draw from this documentary work, and those conclusions to be drawn internationally as a means for dealing with past human rights abuse (Orentlicher 1991). Although operating within distinct legal and political frameworks at the time, each of the regimes of post conflict reconstruction, human rights and international criminal law contributed to the emergence of an overarching conceptual field of transitional justice (McEvoy 2007)- one which sought to reconcile the key aims of each of these disciplines or endeavours within a coherent conceptual framework. It is in this immediate post Cold War period that a distinctive normative concept begins to emerge, resting on the twin pillars of providing justice for victims of human rights abuse while also supporting the emergence of democracy. Arthur, in her conceptual history of the field, suggests that those who were involved in debates at the time regarded the project as offering an intellectual framework that was previously absent for discussing issues that were raised in postwar societies such as Germany, Spain, Greece and Argentina (Arthur 2009, p 327). It was in this period, however, that law and legalism began to colonise the field. Transitional justice was initially narrowly defined, dealing solely with judicial responses to human rights abuse and operating alongside other regimes of post conflict reconstruction, such as state building and democratisation that operated in a less legal and more politically oriented framework. Transitional justice emerged as an international criminal law response to human rights abuse, entailing a strict understanding of “justice” as “criminal justice”. Transitional “justice”, in the form of prosecution for past human rights abuse, was simply one among many divergent tools that could be used to move a state from conflict to peace, as evidenced in the separate frameworks for action. Gradually, however, the scope of transitional justice expanded. Criminal prosecutions came to be seen as a means to address more broadly defined ideas of political and social transformation (Akhavan 1998), and the debate centred around the opposition between peace and justice. This then moved on to a division between truth and justice, and the extent to which truth either represented or denied justice. With each new step the field of transitional justice expanded to incorporate a broader range of objectives. The interplay of these seemingly oppositional concepts exposed the way in which the boundaries of transitional justice were subject to the ongoing and contested interpretation. For example, as seemingly peripheral concepts such as truth and reconciliation jostled for position and were represented as integral to justice rather than opposed to it, the parameters for inclusion within the definition of transitional justice expanded. In so doing transitional justice also began to encompass many of the political elements it had previously worked alongside (Bell 2009; cf IJTJ 2007). They became subsumed into a much broader narrative of transition, increasingly 5 regulated by law. This broadened (international) mandate was confirmed in the 2004 Report of the Secretary General on Transitional Justice and the Rule of Law in Conflict and Post Conflict Societies in which the goals of transitional justice were explicitly linked with those of peace and democracy, and in particular with the consolidation of the rule of law. Bell sums this development up as follows: “The attempt to find and articulate a common legal framework gave rise to a situation where particularised relationships between dealing with the past and constitutional settlement ... were narrated as part of the one phenomenon of how to account for the past and satisfy international standards.” (Bell 2009, p 16). This was all done within the framework of increased emphasis on rule of law responses to conflict, increasingly through the implementation of international law standards (UN 2004 & 2011).Adopting a more broadly defined purpose and modus operandi was central to the evolution of the concept, which is in large part defined by this mandate of achieving peaceful and lasting change in transitional societies. The centrality of this mandate can be seen clearly in the theorisation of the concept of transitional justice. b. Theorisation of the model In 2000 Ruti Teitel published her seminal text Transitional Justice, in which she outlined what she saw as an emerging conception of the field and its core underlying assumptions. This text is chosen as illustrative of thinking in the field at the time. Teitel brings together discussion of previously disparate mechanisms for dealing with the past, including trials, truth commissions, lustration and constitutional reform, each of which had their own distinct aims and objectives, and discusses them within the new conceptual framework of transitional justice. A significant focus of this inquiry is the role that law can play in facilitating political transition. From the year 2000 transitional justice, it has been argued, has existed as a “self conscious field of practice and study...” (Bell 2009, p 8) the label used to denote a general conception of justice in political transition characterised by legal responses to past injustice (Teitel 2000). In particular the shift that occurred at this time was one from viewing justice that operated alongside other political mechanisms in transition, to transitional justice as necessary to deliver successful transitions – peace through justice. In particular, Teitel’s conceptualisation of the field highlights the shift in understandings of the role of law in post conflict situations, moving away from existing and clearly defined regimes of legality to one which is more contingent and shaped by the circumstances in which it operates. The re- conception of law as fluid and capable of providing a framework for transformation laid the foundations for the domination of the field by law. Once the traditional rigidity of law and legal process had been stripped away almost any reform or transformative initiative could be justified using the mantle of law. From the turn of the century what has emerged is a new juridical concept of transitional justice. The emergence of this concept represents a performative event of considerable force in international law. The effect of this performative event has been the delimitation of a “theatrical space” within which all efforts at peace making must play out (Derrida 2001, p 29). The effect of this performative force is not limited to the evolution of the academic discourse of transitional justice. In very practical 6 terms the conceptualisation of transitional justice as a distinct field of endeavour has profoundly influenced the way in which it has developed in practice. The two are therefore integrally linked. The emergence of a theorised concept of transitional justice represented the constitution of a new field, a new way of constructing meaning in relation to justice. Once a normative element was established in transitional justice literature, all efforts at peacemaking became subject to evaluation according to the requirements of that framework itself. This was clearly evident in respect of the belief in the rule of law inherent in transitional justice thinking. This new international order facilitated the emergence of new normative frameworks for action and evaluation (see generally Bell 2006). Despite the existence of a complex web of interrelated claims to the genesis and aims of transitional justice, an overarching narrative emerged dominant, evidenced in a convergence of opinion that certain unifying principles of justice in transition exist and that these normative principles are embodied in mechanisms such as trials, truth commissions and reparations (Subotic 2012, p 120). Transitional justice initiatives could be evaluated on the extent to which they delivered “justice” as defined in international law and action in transitional contexts came to be legitimated by the label of transitional justice. In this way the emergence of the model of transitional justice can be seen as a performative event – a coup de force or rupture with the preceding order (Derrida 1992). The coup de force was one in which the role of politics which had been the dominant force both nationally and internationally, was usurped by that of law. The way in which this force was legitimised, however, was the promise of a new beginning, that the new model of transitional justice represented a new system to replace the corrupt or immoral system it replaced (Douzinas 2005, p 175). In this way the field of transitional justice holds itself apart from earlier (failed) models which are found wanting in terms of their compliance with set standards of justice. The new model represents a break from the need to trade justice against peace, and promises a future in which peace will be based on justice. The emergence of this concept of transitional justice is also intimately linked with the narration of the “end of history” whereby the end of ideological conflict created the conditions for a universalised and post political language of human rights and international justice (Turner 2011). The implications of the performative force of transitional justice remain as yet unclear. Derrida himself acknowledges that the force of the emergence of related concepts such as “crime against humanity” or even “human rights” can be seen either as “an immense progress, an historic transformation” or alternatively as “a concept still obscure in its limits, fragile in its foundations”(Derrida 2001, p 30).What is clear, however, is that with the emergence of the model of transitional justice came an exclusionary force whereby those who seek redress must do so in the language of transitional justice, thus inherently delimiting the narration of violence and justice (Nagy 2008, p 276). The effect of this is homogenising (McCormick 2001, p 406). Where one concept or one way of seeing the world is placed at the centre of meaning and prioritised over all other ways of thinking, the effect is to marginalise or exclude all other ways of interpreting meaning. The pursuit of the foundational concept becomes a quest for absolute truth which can legitimise subsequent action as neutral and just. This is characterised by the belief that there is one self evident meaning of justice, 7 and one correct way to pursue it, and alternative approaches are marginalised from debate (Fitzpatrick 2005). Transitional justice, despite (or perhaps because of) attempts to introduce greater interdisciplinarity into the field (Bell 2009), remains a resolutely legal field, resting on a number of core assumptions surrounding the capacity of law to mediate social change. 3. Setting the Boundaries –Transitional Justice and the Role of Law As outlined, the unifying feature of transitional justice has become the idea that law can be a means to achieve justice. The promotion of the rule of law through international human rights norms underpins the entire discourse of transitional justice. It is therefore worth explaining in more detail how the role of law is characterised in transitional justice and how law is viewed as responding to the particular circumstances of post conflict societies. Transitional justice rests on the paradox that it seeks to address past failings of the law by replacing it with law. While transitional justice may operate in contexts where law and order has irreparably broken down, in many conflicted societies what is at issue is not the existence of the law but rather its legitimacy in the eyes of the population. Legitimacy may be contested, with ongoing struggle for “ownership” of the law, leaving debates polarised between those who seek to maintain the continuity of law and those who reject the legality of the existing law and demand reform or overthrow of the system (Turner 2010). To try and mediate this dispute, the role of law (and indeed the rule of law) in transition has been vested with particular meaning whereby the stability and continuity of the “rule of law” is maintained, but the substance of the law is re-envisaged as a substantive model that encompasses clearly defined principles of justice. As Teitel states, the role of law in transitional contexts is to “mediate the normative shift in values that characterises these extraordinary periods.” (Teitel 2000, p 11). Law in transition is constructed in relation to the nature of the injustice of the previous regime, deemed to be illegitimate and discredited. This, according to Teitel, provides legitimacy for legal change. What is being advanced, therefore, is not only a shift in understanding of the politics of law in the transitional phase, but also a fundamental shift in understandings of the role and function of law itself. One of the core and accepted premises of transitional justice is that the role of law in transition is fundamentally different from that in ordinary or settled regimes. The operation of law in transition speaks directly to the idea that there is a need to move from one form of society to another, thus responding to the history and narrative of conflict and therefore law. Teitel highlighted three key features of law in transition. These were that law was socially constructed; that international law could transcend domestic legal understandings; and finally that the rule of law could transcend politics. a. Law and the Model of Transition The concept of transitional justice emerged as an overarching conceptual framework for negotiating the move from war, conflict or repression, to a more peaceful society. However as discussed above, the emergence of concept of transition, and consequently of transitional justice, represents a moment of performative force, a moment at which new boundaries are 8 imposed on the meaning of political reform. Once this moment of performative force has occurred, the new concept comes to legitimise all subsequent meaning invested in the concept. However to maintain this, an ongoing act of interpretation is required. In practical terms this means that transitional mechanisms are evaluated within the new parameters of transitional justice, but in conceptual terms it means that the necessity for these mechanisms and reforms must also be interpreted in light of the concept. This ongoing process of interpretation represents a constative force whereby the force of the establishment of the concept itself is constantly re-affirmed through these processes of interpretation (Derrida 1992). It is therefore necessary for the discourse of transitional justice to be justified with reference to the boundaries of meaning established by the origin of the field. Once a concept has been established, once the field had been constituted, the concept assumes legal form of its own. To survive and establish its own authority it must become independent of its history, must assume institutional form in its own right (Derrida 2002, p 47-48). This means that although the force of the origin remains inscribed within the concept itself, the implementation of the new law is re-interpreted as a necessity, as a demand of legality (Douzinas 2005, p 175). This process of interpretation at once conceals and perpetuates the originary force with which the concept was constituted, thus revealing the “differential contamination” between performative force and its preservation (Derrida 1992, p 42). In seeking to deconstruct the relationship between the foundation of law and its ongoing authority, Derrida suggests that there can be no rigorous separation of these two types of force, but rather that the story of the origin of the law will be continually repeated in order to reinforce the legitimacy of the law. The way in which the performative force is maintained is clearly visible in the way in which the role of law in transition has been conceptualised by scholars of transitional justice, and in particular how the role of law has been framed to maintain the distinctness of transitional justice. Central to transitional justice is the idea of a shift from one illegitimate form of government to a more democratic order. Fundamentally, it is assumed that there is a gap between the “law as written” and “law as perceived”- the legitimacy of the law depends on popular understandings of legality. This gap between law and popular perceptions give rise to many of the key antinomies of transitional justice (Campbell & Ní Aoláin 2005). Of particular note are the distinctions between the “is” and the “ought” of law, and between procedural and substantive democracy. These are held out as the key points of tensions in repressive or conflicted societies, the points around which conflict over the legitimacy of law is most likely to arise. These distinctions are also integral to the raison d’etre of transitional justice in that it is precisely these gaps that transitional justice aims to close, using legal form itself to move from one form of legality to another. This is not an altogether uncontroversial claim from a legal point of view. All instances of transitional justice will give rise to conflict over the desirability of maintaining legal certainty as opposed to justifying a new and distinctive conception of law forged in response to an existing set of circumstances, one clearly rooted in history and narrativity. To try and obviate some of this criticism, transitional justice theorists have sought to shift the locus of legal legitimacy from the domestic order to the international, looking particularly to international human rights law as a standard external to the parties which can provide guidance on the necessary course of action (Bell et al 2004, p 306). 9 International human rights law is regarded as a means of bridging the gap in understandings of the role and function of law in transition. Whereas the antinomies of positive and natural law, and procedural and substantive law present dilemmas for the domestic law theorist, Teitel suggests that international law can successfully mediate this tension. She states; “grounded in positive law but incorporating values of justice associated with natural law, international law mediates the rule of law dilemma.”(Teitel 2000, p 21). This emphasis on the incorporation of the values of justice into the substance of law both highlights the link being made in transitional justice between law and justice, but also the fundamental shift from established notions of legality. Where the legality, rather than the existence, of the law is called into question, the new regime speaks directly to the experience of injustice or repression, implicitly acknowledging the failure of law in the past. The role of international law is simply to ease the passage of this new vision of legality, providing as it does independent standards against which the action can be judged (Bell et al 2004, p 308). The importance of incorporating international law, and with it values of justice, in a transitional context is also reflected in Teitel’s third understanding of the role of law in transition – that it is capable of transcending the passing politics of the time. This understanding goes to the heart of transitional justice, and in particular the use of law to achieve transitional outcomes. “Rule of Law” is viewed as a means of simultaneously preserving the continuity of legal form yet marking a break from the old regime and enabling normative change. Although critical of the turn to legalism, McEvoy succinctly outlines what he terms the “seductive qualities of legalistic analysis”. He states “Claims that the rule of law speaks to values and working practices such as justice, objectivity, uniformity, rationality etc are particularly prized in times of profound social and political transition.” (McEvoy 2007, p 417) Although Teitel and others acknowledge the politically contingent nature of law in transition, most agree that law fulfils an important symbolic function in such contexts. Campbell and Ní Aoláin see law in transition as providing the means to confront human rights abuses through the application of legal procedure to narrative forums, and providing a “safe and stable” means to assist the journey (Campbell & Ní Aoláin 2005, p 188). The conception of law in the transitional justice literature is also regarded as a key source of democratic legitimacy. Rather than being held hostage to politics, the application of legal form is seen as a means of transcending existing political conflict and allowing a society to move towards a new form of governance, shielded by the formality of law and legal procedure. The rule of law is represented as providing a new site of contestation, bounded by legality. In this way the interpretation of the role of law in transition ensures the ongoing constitution of the field. Transitional justice, as outlined, above, emerged in attempts to deliver legal accountability at times of political change. It is therefore foreseeable that the field should be concerned with maintaining its essence of legal normativity. This is done through the juxtaposition of law with politics in transitional contexts. Law is represented as embodying values of justice that are absent from politics. It is further portrayed as a necessary means of transcending politics and ensuring that just outcomes are achieved. Each time law is interpreted or applied in this way the performative force of the concept of transitional justice 10 is repeated. The patterns of inclusion and exclusion inherent in the constitution of the field are replicated through the interpretation of some mechanisms as falling legitimately within the scope of transitional justice and others as falling outside that scope (for examples of this tension see Dugard 1997; Sarkin 2001). Politics remains the excluded trace which helps to define the limits of transitional justice. This contrast with politics helps to provide law in transition with its own identity, uniqueness and unity. The boundaries of transitional justice are determined by a system of positive laws and conventions which define its character (Derrida 1987). It must be clearly visible what is contained within the concept and what remains outside. This limitedness provides the basis for the legitimacy, and for the acceptance of the idea of transitional justice as a distinct field, as separate from passing politics and therefore having the capacity to deliver change (Davies 2001). The legitimacy of this new model of transitional justice depends on it being able to distinguish itself from other values such as politics and morality. The definition of conceptual boundaries to the field of transitional justice opens up the possibility for deconstruction of the field itself. The act of naming processes as “transitional justice” serves to further define the boundaries of the field (Derrida 1987). Therefore he or she who is vested with the power of decision making also exercises the power of definition of the very boundaries of the field itself. The moment of decision serves to maintain the structure of the institution. This raises significant questions over who decides, according to what criteria, the content or narrative of transitional justice? Who sets the priorities? And what effect does this have on competing narratives? These questions are not just of rhetorical interest. They illustrate practical difficulties with establishing a normative regime such as transitional justice which has the power to define and shape processes of social reform. b. Law and “Non Paradigmatic” Transitions Analysis of transitions dominated by dichotomy heavily influenced the constitution of the field and the model of transitional justice that emerged. Early transitions represented “paradigmatic” transitions – those punctuated by the antinomies of war and peace; democratic and non-democratic (Campbell & Ní Aoláin 2005, p 182-184). Teitel’s conception of transitional justice in particular assumes that one can reasonably easily distinguish legitimate from illegitimate uses of law, for example, or repressive versus transformed societies. The rise of non-paradigmatic transitions has presented new challenges in terms of the scope and definition of the field. By the end of the twentieth century the nature of the situations to which the label of “transition” was being applied had altered significantly. Rather than dealing with inter state conflict or military dictatorship, the majority of transitional justice activity was arising as a result of negotiated peace settlements (Bell 2000). The end of a conflict by negotiated agreement meant there were no clear winners or losers. Peace agreements rarely spell out precise transitional requirements, therefore while an agreement can serve as a means of bringing transitional justice on to the agenda, fundamental disagreement can remain over its scope and definition. The power of the label of transitional justice can lead to struggle over ownership of the concept itself and conflict over the scope, definition and priority to be afforded to transitional mechanisms (Turner 2010). Take for instance the example of 11 Northern Ireland. Since the signing of the Belfast (or “Good Friday”) Agreement in 1998 Northern Ireland has undergone wide ranging legal reforms aimed at redressing past failures of law. It is common to speak of Northern Ireland as being in transition (Campbell et al. 2003), and yet there remains a distinct tension over the application of the label of transitional justice and the underlying rationale for human rights reforms (Turner 2010). Well documented, for example, is the perception that demands for dealing with the past are simply part of a broader Republican agenda to discredit the state and re-write the narrative of the conflict (Rolston 2006; Simpson 2009). The model of transitional justice assumes a rupture with a prior regime which is held to be discredited on account of breach with public support and perceptions of legality. It also assumes that this moment of rupture, most often the physical manifestation of conflict, can be isolated from political and social dynamics that have preceded it and be addressed as an exceptional event rather than part of ongoing contestation of norms. In these contexts the very definition of transitional justice can make certain courses of action controversial. In particular the idea that transitional justice requires acknowledgement of past failures can be problematic. Transitional justice itself rests on what Derrida terms “semantic instability” (Derrida 2003, p 105). The application of the label of transitional justice will make an inherent value judgement, make pronouncement on the origins and sustenance of the conflict (Bell 2009; Campbell & Ní Aoláin 2005). In this regard the concept of transitional justice itself is revealed as an external force which is brought to bear on post conflict societies. Within this relationship of force Derrida describes how the dominant power is the one that manages to impose and thus legitimate (indeed legalise) on a national or world stage, the terminology, and thus interpretation that best suits it in a given situation (Derrida 2003, p 105). Thus, rather than maintaining a presence that is independent of politics or morality, the distinction between the legal field of transitional justice and the politics that it aims to transcend is revealed to be an illusion. Far from existing independently from history, politics and morality, transitional justice bears within it traces of all of these influences. This can be seen in the use of the terms “acknowledgement” and “denial” – the assumption being that acknowledgement is a necessary component of transitional justice (see generally Derrida 2001). The implicit demand is that one side concede their story, their experience of the conflict and their narrative must give way to that of the other side. Where there are contested narratives of the conflict at play this demand for acknowledgement is not a value free assumption. Applying the label of transitional justice allows one side to take control of the direction of reform in a way that simply replicates the politics and the violence of open conflict. Yet the interpretation of the concept of transitional justice in a way which seeks to apply ostensibly neutral legal principles to mediate reform serves to replicate patterns of inclusion and exclusion on a micro level (Simpson 2007). Adopting one narrative of conflict over another and favouring it through the application of the rhetoric of transition simply represents the maintenance of the original performative force through the process of interpretation. These three understandings of the rule of law in transition demonstrate the way in which law is regarded both as a means to deliver justice for past human rights abuses, and also deliver 12 sustainable political reform in conflicted societies. Law under this conception has a role to play in telling the story of the conflict, in forging narratives of right and wrong and in responding to those charges. The application of legal form is in and of itself regarded as assisting with the establishment of democratic legitimacy and providing a mediated framework for political conflict. 4. Transitional Justice and the Regulative Ideal Knowledge in transitional justice is constructed around the core of a particular conception of justice – that of the application of human rights law to respond to past human rights abuse. This can have a backward looking element, in terms of delivering justice for victims, embodied in mechanisms such as trials and truth commissions, but it also contains a forward looking element where justice is deemed to consist of the application of human rights law in a way which marks a break from a repressive or abusive past and ensures justice in the future, through for example processes of constitutional reform. From either perspective the interpretation of justice that emerges from the transitional justice literature is legal justice. Justice in transition remains determined by legal rules and standards. In addition to this characterisation of the role of law in transition, however, is the way in which transitional justice as a field (or as a concept) has been characterised. Transitional justice mechanisms are represented as the necessary means of achieving or concretising the abstract concept of justice. In this way transitional justice mirrors a Kantian vision of ethically determined action whereby principles of law and political action can be deduced from transcendental standards. This vision of law is evident in Teitel’s claim that international law incorporates standards of justice associated with natural law. Thus “good” law serves as the bridge between the realms of natural justice and positive law. Derrida notes that it is a common presupposition of both natural and positive lawyers that just ends can be achieved by just means (Derrida 1992, p 32). Purportedly natural law principles are transformed into juridical ones, prescribing rules and setting limits on political action. Central to this vision is the assumption that what ought to be done can be done, and that there is an identifiable means of achieving the demands of ethical action (La Caz 2007). This idea of “good” law that can be deduced from the transcendental realm displaces law from the social to the natural realm (Newman 2001, p 17). Rights are viewed as essential, founded in natural law and therefore having an existence that can be determined independently from history or genesis. Law should be universal – applicable to each individual as if it were a universal law of nature. This transcendental concept of right mediates the relationship between law and politics and becomes the foundation and legitimating concept for the construction of knowledge in respect of right. In this context there is little or no questioning of the right of law (Derrida 1992, p 34). In the case of transitional justice the concept of right takes the form of justice. Following a Kantian logic, there is a standard of justice that can be deduced from transcendental principles and this is translated through law (most notably human rights law). The idea of justice becomes a fixed regulatory ideal, a means of determining action (for a critique of fixed regulatory ideals in this context see Derrida 2003). 13 This idea of a regulatory idea, or rules that can and ought to determine action, speaks directly to the conception of law in transition. Law in transition is represented as marking a fundamental shift from notions of legality, translating transcendental principles into law and providing a more responsive model of law that speaks directly to justice (Teitel 2000, p21). In this way the relationship between ethics (or right) and politics is mediated by law, represented as being based on neutral and impartial principles. Law, following this logic, can therefore legitimately regulate politics. To this extent the form or structure of law (the law of law) is significant. Law is portrayed as having its own unique identity separate to politics and morality. It is this that vests it with its authority and allows it to mediate this divide between transcendental ethical principles and empirical political action. For example, the reduction of human rights to writing increases certainty in what exactly human rights are. In this way the transcendental requirements of justice are translated into the empirical reality of law. Rights are no longer simply the subject of philosophical speculation, they exist because they are posited in internationally ratified instruments. The boundaries of this law are defined by criteria established by positive law and convention (Derrida 1987). As a result law should be capable of providing justifiable solutions to the problems of transition. Similarly, monitoring bodies may engage in interpretation of the precise scope and requirements of posited rights (Mechlem 2009). There can be authoritative and legitimate pronouncement on the content of the right. This again means that rights are not subject to political horse trading but are rather the subject of clearly defined legal obligation. Adjudication can be undertaken on the basis of a legally determined rule, independent of political influence. This separation of legal arguments from political or moral arguments is regarded as a key means of overcoming disagreement (Kingsbury 2002). Where there is a clash or competing conception of right, of morality or of justice, that which is enshrined in law will prevail. Where balancing is required this can be undertaken within the parameters of law itself, under the doctrine of relative indeterminacy. The simple fact of having to balance rights should not undermine the objectivity of the law per se. For transitional justice scholars, the rule of law is regarded as transcending politics and in particular as fulfilling and important symbolic function. Precisely because of the inevitable disagreement over the meaning of justice in transitional societies, law steps in to replace politics as the basis for authoritative decisions (Kingsbury 2002). This apparent depoliticisation of law is a central feature of transitional justice. In the drive towards justice, politics is to be neutralised. Principles of justice are the foundations upon which the new state is to be constructed. They are represented as neutral and objective principles against which the success of transition can be measured (Turner 2008). In this way justice forms an ethical horizon, a pre-determined outcome achieved through the implementation of legal rules. However it is with this question of the foundation of the law that cracks begin to emerge in this concept of law in transition. Transitional societies are defined by political conflict. Where transitional justice mechanisms have sought to foster political reconciliation through legal means, this has often been at the expense of genuine political engagement. The idea of justice, understood as legal justice, is so securely rooted in the foundations of transitional justice that it leaves no space for the ongoing contestation of these concepts of right, law or justice themselves (Sokoloff 2005). In transitional contexts the temptation is to maintain stability at all costs, even where this 14 prevents any meaningful engagement with the underlying assumptions of the transitional project. Politics is relegated to the sidelines of public life, viewed as a threat to the stability of the rule of law (see generally Chandler 2000). The distinction between law and justice collapses, and law becomes the dominant means of regulating difference It is the foundation and inherent limitations of this vision of law that a deconstructive analysis reveals. Deconstruction reveals how law and the discourse of transitional justice, rather than transforming violent conflict, conceal violence at their very foundation. a. Transitional justice as autoimmunity? As outlined, transitional justice aims to be both backward and forward looking. Central to the rationale for transitional justice is the idea that it not only responds to past events but that it seeks to prevent those events from recurring in the future. Seen in this way transitional justice responds to traumatism where the evil comes from the possibility of repetition (Derrida 2003). Although ostensibly seeking redress for past injustice, transitional justice is equally concerned with guarantees of non-recurrence (United Nations 2011). The emphasis placed on rule of law underscores the sense of threat posed by failure to deal with past events and therefore risk a return to violence. In order to address this threat, transitional justice mechanisms such as trials and truth commissions set limits of temporal jurisdiction which define the scope of the events to which a response is required. In doing this the discourse seeks to isolate a certain set of events and represent them as extraordinary, as something which had a beginning and an end and which are somehow separate from normal politics. The events under investigation are represented as fleeting, as simply one event in a long history that must be dealt with and moved on from. In doing this, however, it can be argued that transitional justice itself simply ends up reproducing and regenerating patterns of conflict which it seeks to disarm (Derrida 2003). This is seen in the way in which law is relied upon as the means of achieving justice, in particular the way in which the boundaries of the concept of transitional justice are defined to exclude not only alternative mechanisms for dealing with political conflict, but also to silence dissenting voices that do not fit neatly into the narrative of transition. Inclusion and exclusion from the new political regime is shaped by the narrative of transition and the extent to which groups and individuals are willing or able to articulate their positions in the language of transitional justice. In the quest to immunise against recurrence, transitional justice adopts rigid structures which may ultimately work to destroy that immunity. The desire to achieve closure on past events, to reach a solution in the present that will safeguard the future places boundaries or limits on the possibility of justice. b. Law is not the same as justice The pursuit of human rights in transition tends towards the equation of law, and the implementation of international human rights law, with justice. This is evidenced most clearly in the drive towards legal mechanisms for responding to trauma. International blueprints provide frameworks for justice that reduced the singular to the general- that impose generalised rules, norms and universalised imperatives on societies “in transition”. 15 The originary concept of transitional justice provides a determinate existence – a solid foundation –for the system of meaning, and for the interpretation of “justice”. The assumption that underlies this model of transitional justice is that the application of rules and programmes for action is a means of achieving justice. When seen through a deconstructive lens, the effect of this, while seeking to achieve the impossible – seeking to achieve justice - is simply to deliver the possible in its place (De Ville 2008, p 105). What this means is that in the effort to enshrine principles of justice into the originary act of founding a law (the terms of reference for a tribunal or truth commission, or the drafting of a constitution, for example), a regulatory horizon of expectation is imposed In this act the essence of justice is lost. The imposition of calculated rules buries the possibility of justice (Derrida 1992). Once the outcome of law becomes fixed and determinate the responsiveness that allows law to pursue justice is lost. This is not to suggest that there should be no normative orientation to transitional justice. Rather what is central is the ability to recognise the potentially coercive effects of the determinate element of law. Relying too heavily, or without question, on law and the inviolability of law, can deny the responsiveness of law and reduce it to an ultimately arbitrary standard. Where law, or any other determinate concept, comes to be regarded as fixed and inviolate, the risk is that the centrality of this concept ceases to be subjected to scrutiny (Sokoloff, 2005). The ongoing process of questioning that Derrida advocates as necessary in order to achieve justice is lost, and with it the ability of law to deliver meaningful change. As Fitzpatrick states, “’In God We Trust’ can relieve us of trusting each other” (Fitzpatrick 2005). The unquestioning acceptance of norms and systems becomes not only possible but commonplace. In situations defined by political conflict, by competing narratives, placing too great an emphasis on the application of norms also absolves responsibility for openness to the other. Where ones position can be reinforced by reference to law there is no longer any need to engage with the other. As Derrida himself describes, “droit claims to exercise itself in the name of justice and ... justice is required to establish itself in the name of a law that must be enforce.”(Derrida 1992, p 22). Transitional justice scholars have tended to equate justice with law, or to view justice as something that can be achieved through the enforcement of human rights law. However, to the extent that justice can be present in law and (reformed) institutions, it is only as a possibility (Derrida 1992). It should not be treated as an identifiable end point such as a particular model of democracy or governance, or as the enforcement of legal rights. Justice should have no horizon of expectation, regulative or messianic (Derrida 1992, p 27). Justice represents a call to a more consequential change “not simply in the naïve sense of calculated, deliberate and strategically controlled intervention, but in the sense of maximum intensification of a transformation in progress, in the name of neither a simple symptom nor simple cause.” (Derrida 1992, p 9). 16 5. Conclusion : The (Im)possibility of Transitional Justice? Derrida himself suggested in Force of Law that it was “foreseeable and desirable that studies of deconstructive style should culminate in the problematic of law and justice” (Derrida 1992, p 7). It seems equally foreseeable and desirable that studies of transitional justice should culminate in deconstruction of the concepts of law and justice on which the field is founded, for deconstruction itself is a problematisation of the foundations of law, morality and politics. In the preceding sections it has been shown how questions of law, morality and politics are intimately linked in the context of transitional justice, to the extent that rigid distinction between the concepts themselves can no longer withstand scrutiny. In transitional justice the urge must be resisted to look for determinate frameworks of justice. Law, and human rights law in particular, should not be instrumentally subordinated to a determined outcome. Law must remain open to the possibility of justice. For justice exceeds rules and calculations. It is not simply a juridical or a political concept, but it opens up for the future the possibility of transformation, of re-casting or re-founding law and politics. The challenge to remain open to critical engagement is rooted in the idea of an infinite idea of justice that is irreducible to law. It is in this ongoing process of questioning that justice lies – in the openness to the other, the existence of whom is immanent to the idea of transition. In this way deconstruction is transitional justice. Acknowledgements I would like to thank Sara Ramshaw, Louise Mallinder and Ilan Rua Wall for comments on an earlier draft of this paper. All errors or contested interpretations remain my own. References: Akhavan, Payam. 1998. Justice in The Hague, Peace in the former Yugoslavia? A Commentary on the United Nations War Crimes Tribunal. Human Rights Quarterly 20: 737 Arthur, Paige. 2009. How ‘Transitions” Reshaped Human Rights: A Conceptual History of Transitional Justice. Human Rights Quarterly 31: 321 Beardsworth, Richard. 1996. Derrida and the Political. London: Routledge. Bell, Christine. 2000. Peace Agreements and Human Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bell, Christine. 2006. ‘Negotiating Justice? Human Rights and Peace Agreements’. Geneva: International Council on Human Rights Policy. Bell, Christine. 2009. Transitional Justice, Interdisciplinarity and the State of the ‘Field’ or ‘Non Field’ International Journal of Transitional Justice 3:5 Bell, Christine, Colm Campbell and Finonuala Ní Aoláin. 2004. Justice Discourses in Transition Social and Legal Studies 13(3) 305 Campbell, Colm et al. 2003. The Frontiers of Legal Analysis: Reframing the Transition in Northern Ireland. Modern Law Review 66: 317 17 Campbell, Colm and Fionnuala Ní Aoláin. 2005. The Paradox of Transition in Conflicted Democracies. Human Rights Quarterly 27: 172 Chandler, David. 2000. Bosnia: Faking Democracy After Dayton. Pluto Press. Dancy, Geoff. 2010. Impact Assessment, Not Evaluation: Defining a Limited Role for Positivism in the Study of Transitional Justice. International Journal of Transitional Justice 4: 355 Davies, Margaret. 2001. Derrida and Law: Legitimate Fictions. In Jacques Derrida and the Humanities: A Critical Reader ed, Tom Cohen 213-237. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Derrida, Jacques. 1987. Before the Law. In Kafka and the Contemporary Critical Performance ed A Udoff. Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press. Derrida, Jacques. 1992. Force of Law: The Mystical Foundation of Authority. In Deconstruction and the Possibility of Justice, ed Drucilla Cornell. New York: Routledge. Derrida, Jacques. 2001. On Cosmopolitanism and Forgiveness. Trans Mark Dooley and Michael Hughes. London: Routledge. Derrida, Jacques. 2002. Declarations of Independence. In Negotiations, Interventions and Interviews, 1971-2001 ed E Rottenbert. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Derrida, Jacques. 2003. Autoimmunity: Real and Symbolic Suicides. In Philosophy in a Time of Terror: Dialogues with Jurgen Habermas and Jacques Derrida ed, Giovanna Borradori 85-136. Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press. De Ville, Jacques. 2008. Sovereignty Without Sovereignty: Derrida’s Declarations of Independence. Law and Critique 19: 87 Douzinas, Costas. 2005. Violence, Justice, Deconstruction. German Law Journal 6: 171 Dugard, John. 1997. Retrospective Justice: International Law and the South African Model. In Transitional Justice and the Rule of Law in New Democracies ed AJ McAdams. University of Notre Dame Press. Fitzpatrick, Peter. 2005. In God we trust’ can relieve us of trusting each other: Peter Fitzpatrick interviewed by Jill Stauffer. The Believer 3 (8): 63-72. IJTJ. 2007. Editorial Note. International Journal of Transitional Justice 1:1 Kingsbury, Benedict. 2002. Legal Positivism as Normative Politics: International Society, Balance of Power and Lassa Oppenheim’s Positive International Law. European Journal of International Law 13(2): 401 La Caz, Margarite. 2007. At the Intersection: Kant, Derrida and the Relation Between Ethics and Politics. Political Theory 35: 781 McCormick, John. 2001. Derrida on Law: Or, Poststructuralism Gets Serious. Political Theory 29: 395 McEvoy, Kieran. 2007. Transitional Justice From Below: Towards a Thicker Understanding of Transitional Justice. Journal of Law and Society 34: 411 Mechlem, Kerstin. 2009. Treaty Bodies and the Interpretation of Human Rights. Vanderbilt Journal of Transnational Law 42: 905 Nagy, Rosemary. 2008. Transitional Justice as Global Project: Critical Reflections. Third World Quarterly 29: 275 18 Newman, Saul. 2001. Derrida’s Deconstruction of Authority. Philosophy and Social Criticism 27(3):1 Orentlicher, Diane. 1991. Settling Accounts: The Duty to Prosecute Human Rights Violations of a Prior Regime. Yale Law Journal 100: 2539 Rolston, Bill. 2006. Dealing with the Past: Pro State Paramilitaries, Truth and Transition in Northern Ireland. Human Rights Quarterly 28: 652 Sarkin, Jeremy. 2001. The Tension Between Justice and Reconciliation in Rwanda: Politics, Human Rights, Due Process and the Role of Gacaca Courts in Dealing with the Genocide. Journal of African Law 45: 143 Simpson, Kirk. 2007. Voices Silenced, Voices Re-Discovered: Victims of Violence and the Reclamation of Language in Transitional Societies. International Journal of Law in Context 3: 89 Simpson, Kirk (2009) Unionist Voices and the Politics of Remembering the Past in Northern Ireland. Basingstoke: Palgrave MacMillan Sokoloff, William. 2005. Between Justice and Legality: Derrida on Decision. Political Research Quarterly 58: 341 Subotic, Jelena. 2012. The Transformation of International Transitional Justice Advocacy. International Journal of Transitional Justice 6: 106 Teitel, Ruti. 2000. Transitional Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Teitel, Ruti. 2003. Transitional Justice Genealogy. Harvard Human Rights Journal 16: 69 Turner, Catherine. 2008. Delivering Lasting Peace, Democracy and Human Rights in Transition: The Role of International Law. International Journal of Transitional Justice 2: 126 Turner, Catherine. 2010. Political Representations of Law in Northern Ireland. Public Law 451 Turner, Catherine. 2011. Human Rights and the Empire of (International) Law. Law and Inequality 29: 311 United Nations. 2004. ‘Report of the Secretary General on Transitional Justice and the Rule of Law in Conflict and Post Conflict Societies’. UN Doc S/2004/616 United Nations. 2011. ‘Report of the Secretary General on Transitional Justice and Rule of Law in Conflict and Post Conflict Societies’. UN Doc S/2011/634 work_in6luqd3gbhkzbsbtqsq5vxt4a ---- wp-p1m-39.ebi.ac.uk Params is empty 404 sys_1000 exception wp-p1m-39.ebi.ac.uk no 221735658 Params is empty 221735658 exception Params is empty 2021/04/06-03:20:33 if (typeof jQuery === "undefined") document.write('[script type="text/javascript" src="/corehtml/pmc/jig/1.14.8/js/jig.min.js"][/script]'.replace(/\[/g,String.fromCharCode(60)).replace(/\]/g,String.fromCharCode(62))); // // // window.name="mainwindow"; .pmc-wm {background:transparent repeat-y top left;background-image:url(/corehtml/pmc/pmcgifs/wm-nobrand.png);background-size: auto, contain} .print-view{display:block} Page not available Reason: The web page address (URL) that you used may be incorrect. Message ID: 221735658 (wp-p1m-39.ebi.ac.uk) Time: 2021/04/06 03:20:33 If you need further help, please send an email to PMC. Include the information from the box above in your message. Otherwise, click on one of the following links to continue using PMC: Search the complete PMC archive. Browse the contents of a specific journal in PMC. Find a specific article by its citation (journal, date, volume, first page, author or article title). http://europepmc.org/abstract/MED/ work_inzbsvb2anesni7u6n44xgeffu ---- wp-p1m-39.ebi.ac.uk Params is empty 404 sys_1000 exception wp-p1m-39.ebi.ac.uk no 221741154 Params is empty 221741154 exception Params is empty 2021/04/06-03:20:40 if (typeof jQuery === "undefined") document.write('[script type="text/javascript" src="/corehtml/pmc/jig/1.14.8/js/jig.min.js"][/script]'.replace(/\[/g,String.fromCharCode(60)).replace(/\]/g,String.fromCharCode(62))); // // // window.name="mainwindow"; .pmc-wm {background:transparent repeat-y top left;background-image:url(/corehtml/pmc/pmcgifs/wm-nobrand.png);background-size: auto, contain} .print-view{display:block} Page not available Reason: The web page address (URL) that you used may be incorrect. Message ID: 221741154 (wp-p1m-39.ebi.ac.uk) Time: 2021/04/06 03:20:40 If you need further help, please send an email to PMC. Include the information from the box above in your message. Otherwise, click on one of the following links to continue using PMC: Search the complete PMC archive. Browse the contents of a specific journal in PMC. Find a specific article by its citation (journal, date, volume, first page, author or article title). http://europepmc.org/abstract/MED/ work_iovil2ito5f6hkl5wqe6dvjsj4 ---- Globalizing environmental justice? Geoforum 54 (2014) 151–157 CORE Metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk Provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector Contents lists available at ScienceDirect Geoforum j o u r n a l h o m e p a g e : w w w . e l s e v i e r . c o m / l o c a t e / g e o f o r u m Editorial Globalizing environmental justice? http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.geoforum.2014.04.009 0016-7185/� 2014 The Authors. Published by Elsevier Ltd. This is an open access article under the CC BY-NC-ND license (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/). There is now a long and rich history of practice and theory com- monly associated with the concept of environmental justice. Much of it has focused on the global North, and the US in particular, reflecting the origins of movements that carry the label and that have invoked the discourse of environmental justice (Cole and Foster, 2001; Agyeman, 2005; Bullard, 2005). These origins imply a key preoccupation with racial inequality due to the apparently unique history of the US in terms of civil rights struggles and an emphasis on a particular set of environmental problems, such as the location of hazardous waste sites. Nonetheless, environmental justice has increasingly served as a crucial rallying ground for social activism and political resistance beyond the US in parts of Latin America, Asia and South Africa, for example (Agyeman et al., 2003; Agyeman and Ogneva-Himmelberger, 2009; Holifield et al., 2009; Guha and Martinez-Alier, 1997; Martinez-Alier, 2002; McDonald, 2002; Carruthers, 2008). Research on place-specific struggles over natural resources and environmental mobilizations suggest that ‘the core issues at the heart of environmental justice struggles are universal’ (Schroeder et al., 2008; cf. Guha and Martinez-Alier, 1999; Walker and Bulkeley, 2006). Justice provides local communities and environ- mental activists with an important vocabulary in their resistance against dispossession from customary land, opposition to polluting industries and struggles for a fair distribution of natural resource revenues. Even where resistance is not couched in justice terms, ‘everyday’ struggles and mobilizations over environmental degra- dation and natural resource exploitation are often about the distri- bution of environmental bads and goods, participation in decision making and recognition of particular group identities and histories, which constitute the classic concerns of environmental justice (Schlosberg, 2004, 2007). Environmental justice thus may provide a powerful lens through which to make sense of struggles over environments and natural resources worldwide, providing a link between Northern literature on environmental justice and research on southern environmentalisms (Guha and Martinez-Alier, 1997; Guha, 1999), and between the ‘environmentalism of the poor’ (Martinez-Alier, 2002), liberation ecology (Peet and Watts, 2004) and global political ecology (Peet et al., 2011a). This special issue starts from the premise that environmental justice concerns may not only be universal(izing), but also increas- ingly operate at a global scale: creating international political com- munities and finding expression within ‘global’ institutions (Newell, 2006; Walker, 2009). Whilst not overlooking the tremen- dous diversity of meanings and struggles around environmental justice around the world, this claim refers to the growing adoption of discourses and strategies that are associated with, and in many ways derive from, environmental justice movements. Movements around water, food or climate increasingly adopt the language of justice for example, raising explicitly concerns with historical eco- logical debts between and within nations, uneven ecological exchange and the social injustices that arise from the poorest being most vulnerable to the effects of problems to which they have con- tributed very little. Claims of environmental (in)justices are increasingly also deployed within transnational arenas dealing with the issues of trans-border trade and investment, for example, but with consequences for local environmental struggles and polit- ical ecologies. Practices of production, trade and regulation at one site increasingly connect with seemingly distant sites elsewhere through extended supply chains, technology diffusion and the internationalization of production. In so doing they transform the dynamics of inequality: reshaping or entrenching existing forms of inequality, and modifying the spaces available for the pursuit of justice (Newell, 2012). Though the significance of such connec- tions is hardly novel and the history of colonialism could certainly be told in those terms, the point of departure here is the confluence of globalizing discourses of justice and corresponding institutional arrangements to which these claims are directed and which seek to address them, and a globalizing phase of contemporary capitalism which has reconfigured the geographies of environmental (in)jus- tice (Fraser, 2009; Walker and Bulkeley, 2006). In this light, there is a strong case for examining how questions of place-specific environmental justice relate to larger-scale polit- ical and economic processes through globalization and the expand- ing reach of global governance arrangements. It is also insightful to ask how the transnational deployment of claims of environmental (in)justices generates consequences for place-based environmental struggles as well as creating opportunities for occupying and influ- encing national and global political spaces in novel ways. The con- nections work in both directions: local issues and struggles are affected by larger-scale processes, but simultaneously influence the latter since the reputation and capital of global institutions is then invested in the success of interventions in particular locales over which they exercise only partial control and whereupon they are vulnerable to resistance and disruption (Newell and Bumpus, 2012). ‘Local’ and ‘global’, in this sense, are not given attributes of environmental claims, practices and issues, but rather are con- stituted through the scalar practices of particular actors and result- ing processes (Neumann, 2009). It is only through these practices and processes that ‘place-specific policies and practices can have consequences that cross national boundaries, affect multiple scales, and extend across global networks’ (Holifield et al., 2009: 595). This special issue proposes global environmental justice as a lens to make sense of place-specific environmental struggles in their relation to the sorts of broader political economic processes which are often identified as intensifying or accelerating the https://core.ac.uk/display/82474432?utm_source=pdf&utm_medium=banner&utm_campaign=pdf-decoration-v1 http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1016/j.geoforum.2014.04.009&domain=pdf http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.geoforum.2014.04.009 http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/3.0/ http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.geoforum.2014.04.009 http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/journal/00167185 http://www.elsevier.com/locate/geoforum 152 Editorial / Geoforum 54 (2014) 151–157 production of environmental injustices. It does not pretend to pro- vide a comprehensive account of worldwide mobilizations for environmental justice.1 Instead, it seeks to show how practices of environmental (in)justice have changed in ways which may require innovative approaches to research and engagement. Though global- izing tendencies are uneven, environmental injustices are often pro- duced and justice claims invoked in relation to the re-scaling of capital accumulation or the extension of political authority over new swathes of natural resources. They are often ultimately grounded in local and national realities and socio-ecological strug- gles, however. Each contribution to the issue will consequently explore how globalizing practices and processes impact upon spe- cific environmental struggles to develop ways of understanding and explaining the ways in which those struggles are embedded with, and in turn shape, broader global processes. The point of departure for this themed issue, therefore, is the need to think innovatively and in an interdisciplinary way about how to make sense of environmental justice issues as they relate to and are experienced by people all around the world. The concept of ‘global environmental justice’ serves as a lens to critically ana- lyze ongoing economic, political and environmental transforma- tions from multiple disciplinary viewpoints. It combines a focus on the globalizing production of environmental justices and injus- tices and the interest of international political economists in the workings of global networks and institutions with political ecolo- gists’ attention to the specificity of place-based socio-environmen- tal struggles. It also engages debates in political philosophy about justice, particularly recent attention to non-western cultures and their implications for thought and practice on development (e.g. Sen, 2009) and the ways in which mobilizations by sub-altern groups, such as indigenous peoples for example, challenge liberal notions of collective action, citizenship and the pursuit of justice (Yashar, 2005). This introduction develops a substantive framing for the contri- butions to the themed issue, including the research papers and critical reviews. It seeks to provide a brief justification of the ana- lytical traction to be gained from applying a global environmental justice lens, one that brings together key concerns in environmen- tal justice scholarship, political ecology, and international political economy. It develops the justification in three steps, asking first about the utility of ‘justice’, then about the specifically ‘environ- mental’ component of this, and finally asking what an emphasis on the ‘global’ adds to our understanding. Taken together, we argue, the three terms provide a powerful heuristic framework for understanding contemporary environmental politics and the political economy of natural resources. Why ‘justice’? Whether it is ‘climate justice’, ‘food justice’ or ‘water justice’ the language of justice is omnipresent in environmental politics (Bond, 2012; Gottlieb and Joshi, 2010; Boelens et al., 2011). Many contem- porary mobilizations over access to resources (such as seeds, for- ests or water) or objections to uneven exposure to environmental harms (e.g. climate change) employ justice as a discursive frame. The reference provides a useful vehicle for highlighting the justice component of environmental challenges as well as lending legiti- macy to particular struggles. Similarly, transnational conventions and norms increasingly refer to justice, such as those dealing with 1 For interesting and innovative attempts to map environmental justice in this way see EJOLT (Environmental Justice Organisations, Liabilities and Trade, http:// www.ejolt.org/) as well as the connected archive of mining conflicts compiled by OCMAL (Observatorio de Conflictos Mineros de América Latina, http://www.conflic- tosmineros.net/) and Map of Environmental Conflicts in Brazil (http://www.conflito- ambiental.icict.fiocruz.br/). Reducing Emissions from Deforestation and Forest Degradation (REDD+; Okereke and Dooley, 2009; Sikor, 2013a). Most recently, the Parties to the Convention on Biological Diversity (CBD) approved a new protocol on Access and Benefit Sharing in 2010 as a means to address the lack of access to benefits from biodiver- sity to date of many poorer stewards of natural resources (Martin et al., 2013). Opposition to injustices and demands for justice lie at the heart of many place-based struggles around the world. Justice and ideas about justice are a critical element in material and discursive struggles about access to and control over resources (e.g., Berry, 1993; Fortmann, 1995; Peluso, 1996). Poor people’s claims are not only about the distribution of environmental goods and bads, Martinez-Alier (2014) argues, but also about whose visions of the environment are recognized, who participates in environmental decision-making and democracy, and what kinds of values come to matter – all of which are central matters of justice. As important as distributive issues are, however, the claims made by actors in place-based struggles are also often about issues of participation and recognition, reflecting Fraser’s call to think about justice in ways that extend beyond distribution to also include recognition and representation (Fraser, 1997). The plurality of conceptions and practices of justice challenges research to critically interrogate assertions of (in)justices in envi- ronmental struggles. The specific claims made in concrete strug- gles are highly diverse, defying any attempt of defining them in uniform terms (cf. Schlosberg, 2004; Walker and Bulkeley, 2006). As social actors bring different notions of justice to bear upon issues of access to natural resources and exposure to environmen- tal risk, the question arises of which types of actors are able to assert what kinds of claims given the historical circumstances they inherit and the contemporary political economy whose terrain they have to navigate. There is a need to critically examine asser- tions of (in)justice and trace how some assertions find support in public discourse as legitimate demands whereas others do not, or are rejected outright as illegitimate claims (Sen, 2009). The plural- ity of justice, in other words, directs analytical attention to envi- ronmental politics and power relations, as demonstrated by Movik (2014) and Upton (2014). Movik examines competing dis- cursive constructions of water rights in debates surrounding South Africa’s Water Allocation reform, while Upton looks at issues of representation and accountability within the global pastoralists’ movement. The plurality of justice claims also opens up intriguing connections with normative reasoning in political philosophy as a way to distinguish legitimate notions of justice from mere asser- tions of self-interest – or to challenge the increasingly common- place distinction between matters of distribution, participation and recognition, as Martin et al. (2014) point out. Justice and the ability to provide it remains a constitutive ele- ment of the legitimacy of the modern nation state. For example, activists in the US have called on the federal government in sup- port of struggles against unequal exposure to pollution (Williams, 1999). National governments from post-socialist Europe to postcolonial Latin America have recently transferred forest ten- ure to various excluded groups, justifying the transfer as a means of undoing historical injustices (Sikor et al., 2009; Larson et al., 2010). The South African state meanwhile has emerged as a key arena in struggles about water, as the vesting of allocative author- ity with the state has turned the state into a key site for competing claims of (in)justice (Movik, 2014). Likewise, Chhotray (2014) shows how the state’s denial of legal entitlements to assistance critically shapes the ‘relief relationship’ between state and citizens in India. The relief relationship is based on moral concerns over the fate of people affected by super-cyclones and other disasters but not responsibilities enshrined in law. Mehta et al. (2014) go a step further by concluding that the Bolivian and Indian states have http://www.ejolt.org/ http://www.ejolt.org/ http://www.conflictosmineros.net/ http://www.conflictosmineros.net/ http://www.conflitoambiental.icict.fiocruz.br/ http://www.conflitoambiental.icict.fiocruz.br/ Editorial / Geoforum 54 (2014) 151–157 153 abandoned their welfare missions with regard to access to safe and potable water in peri-urban spaces. These cases highlight once again the potential of states to operate both as ‘rights protector’ and ‘rights violator’, posing real dilemmas for activists framing jus- tice claims in the sorts of rights language which implies or requires state enforcement or adjudication (Newell and Wheeler, 2006). This is significant because references to justice often employ the notion of rights and entitlements, from civil rights-based environ- mental mobilizations in the US to the emergent rights agenda in international forestry (Sikor and Stahl, 2011). So-called ‘rights- based approaches’ have gained a prominent place in international development, water management, and most recently biodiversity conservation (cf. Scanlon et al., 2004; Campese et al., 2009; Hickey and Mitlin, 2009). ‘Rights talk’ has become attractive to an increasingly wide range of social and political actors, as claim- ing a right ‘is to register the strongest kind of claim for which our moral language provides’ (Jones, 1994: 49–50). Claims are strengthened further if they can be couched in the language of human right, lending them an essential status that must be respected universally. Nevertheless, rights agendas are only one kind of approach to justice and may not work as envisioned by their promoters, particularly in their individualistic and universal- izing expressions (Yashar, 2005). In this issue, Mehta et al. (2014) and Blaikie and Muldavin (2014) provide critical perspectives on global rights agendas, highlighting the overpowering influence of local and national political economies in diluting the intended effects of rights claims. Mehta et al. (2014) find that the political economic dynamics that produce people’s exclusion from safe drinking water in peri-urban spaces of Bolivia and India also con- strain the leverage of rights-based approaches for overcoming the exclusion. Blaikie and Muldavin (2014) suggest that procedural justice, particularly around ideas of participation, may have gained traction with international donors, but the actual implementation of ideas and procedures is largely shaped by national and local political economies which subvert this intent. At the same time, the ascendance of justice as a discursive frame may also reflect multiplying kinds of environmental injus- tice as a result of a series of interrelated trends. The international- ization of production and technology, accelerated through the removal of trade barriers, brings powerful actors such as multina- tional companies and environmental NGOs into increasing contact with remote and often socially excluded groups whose resources were previously not accessible or exploitable, or were protected by the state. Resource frontiers have been expanded driven by a mixture of scarcity and opportunity as captured in the practice of ‘land grabs’ (White et al., 2012) and ‘green grabs’ (Fairhead et al., 2012). The pursuit of new sites of accumulation, driven by eco- nomic rationales or ecological imperatives (securing future sup- plies of land or water), generate very unequal distributions of access to, and control over, natural resources (Sachs and Santarius, 2005; Martinez-Alier et al., 2010), and uneven contribu- tions and exposures to global environmental change (O’Rourke and Connolly, 2003; Srinivasan et al., 2008). They also create and exac- erbate place-based conflicts where global actors become embroiled in local and national questions of cultural recognition and political self-determination (Newell, 2005, 2007). Conflicts are then as much about whose notions of justice and framings of environmen- tal problems prevail as about competition over access to and con- trol over material resources (Jasanoff and Martello, 2004; Fraser, 2009; Sikor et al., 2013a). Analytically then it is important to examine environmental struggles in justice terms because environmental movements, state actors, business and international organizations employ the language of justice, and because their claims may increasingly reflect a reality in which environmental injustices have multiplied and their geographies been reconfigured. The focus on justice chal- lenges researchers and activists alike to critically interrogate the invocations of justice (or lack thereof), relate justice claims to the specific political economic dynamics generating (in)justices, and ask about what kinds of justice are being asserted, by whom and for whom, particularly if justice claims assert a universal quality. Why ‘environmental’? What then is the specifically environmental component of jus- tice? Often struggles that are labeled environmental are as much about the pursuit of specific social justice claims (Guha and Martinez-Alier, 1999; Rangan, 2004). So, for example, the struggle of the Ogoni people in Niger delta is as much about access to the revenues generated from the oil in their area as it is opposition to the environmental damage caused by oil spills (Okanta and Douglas, 2001). Struggles against the chemical industry in Louisi- ana are as much about human health concerns as the release of chemicals into the environment (Allen, 2003). In practice, most struggles are driven by, and articulate their claims in relation to, a number of grievances since people have different motivations for joining movements, and because the concrete problems con- fronted by people are typically multifaceted. Another element of the question is to what extent claims of (in)justice regarding different natural resources and environmental qualities share similar grounds, or can really be said to be about the ‘environment’ per se as opposed to a particular socio-ecological regime. Even though justice framings have become increasingly important in advocacy on climate change, water, food and genetic resources, for example, the particular injustices that motivate mobilizations retain local peculiarities in their social and environ- mental constitution. The resulting mobilizations, and the processes giving rise to the injustices they address do not fit into a single and neat category of ‘environment’, therefore. There may be significant diversity in the demands asserted by various actors with regards to different kinds of natural resources or environmental qualities and services (Martin, 2013). Just as the historical settings and specific contexts in which environmental struggles take place are diverse, so too are the particular manifestations of the political economic processes producing injustices and shaping the possibilities for jus- tice. Global capitalism is produced by and mediated through par- ticular varieties of capitalism and refracted through alignments of state power and social forces that take on different forms (Panitch and Gindin, 2012). At the same time, framing issues in terms of environmental (in)justice allows mobilizations to tran- scend national borders and attract the attention of wider sets of activists and publics when a local issue gets re-framed as a matter of common interest or global public good. Mulvaney (2014) shows how activists successfully employed an environmental justice framing to link occupational hazards in the Global South with green policy in the U.S. Kumar (2014) also explores how activists assembled connections between local opposition to a mine in India’s Niyamgiri mountains and national and transnational mobi- lizations around a shared commitment to protect the mountains. One of the shared elements of justice claims that most often arises in environmental debates is the significance of inter-gener- ational justice. This framing was explicit in the Brundtland report Our Common Future (1987) which conceived of sustainable devel- opment as being about the ability of current generations to meet their needs without compromising the ability of future generations to meet their own needs. In climate justice struggles justice to future generations is a central mobilizing claim: holding the cur- rent generation of decision-makers and polluters to account now for failing to act and imposing on future generations risks and dan- gers for which they are not responsible (Page, 2006). Struggles around nuclear or toxic waste also highlight the legacies of pollu- tion caused now for future generations as a basis for articulating 154 Editorial / Geoforum 54 (2014) 151–157 justice demands, as do warnings over the depletion of water resources and minerals or herders’ global advocacy around envi- ronmental stewardship (Upton, 2014). Thus, alongside claims of ‘justice to nature’, concerns over the future effects of contemporary actions may set environmental justice apart from other justice claims. Yet it is precisely this inter-generational dimension that has caused some political philosophers to question whether it is mean- ingful to apply the concept of justice to issues of environmental sustainability at all. Justice, the argument goes, is only about dis- tributive issues within the current generation, whereas environ- mental sustainability is about concerns between generations. Preconditions for the latter can be determined scientifically and are therefore not subject to justice concerns (Vincent, 1998; Dobson, 1999). Forsyth (2014) counters this argument in his con- tribution to the themed issue, stressing the need to examine how environmental problems are identified, and how particular fra- mings imply specific understandings of environmental justice. Defining problems such as climate change in particular ways shapes the pursuit of justice by defining unjust risks and proposing just solutions. Forsyth’s argument builds on a vast body of litera- ture on contested understandings of the ‘environment’ exploring questions of whose knowledge counts and whose and what envi- ronment is at stake (cf. Leach et al., 2010). It also speaks to critical findings in research on ‘natural’ disasters that stress their social construction, mediation by political economic forces, as well as people’s differentiated experiences of them (Peet et al., 2011b). As environmental change is understood and experienced in socially differentiated ways, framings and governance interventions embody and reinforce particular understandings of (environmen- tal) justice and the means by which it will be secured, as illustrated by the increasingly popular and contested concept of ecosystem services (Sikor, 2013b). Yet even acknowledging the social construction and differen- tiated experience of environmental problems, the question remains how environmental justice may be different from other fields of justice due to the presence of biophysical dynamics over inter-generational time frames. Non-human agency may distin- guish concerns with environmental justice from more general justice issues. For example, there are elements of risk and uncer- tainty to disasters which cannot be reduced to social construc- tions and political economic mediation. Biophysical dynamics may complicate easy attributions of responsibility and culpabil- ity, lending moral weight to certain claims to assistance on the basis of victimhood (Chhotray, 2014). Non-human nature brings in numerous actants within and beyond human society and across generations, such as in sentient ecologies (Anderson, 2002). Likewise the materiality of resources shapes questions of access and benefit depending on how ‘cooperative’ they are or amenable to exploitation as commodities (Bakker, 2003; Newell and Bumpus, 2012). Thus, there is the need to examine the dynamics associated with specific environmental injustices and critically investigate the nature of environmental justice claims. The focus on environ- mental justice challenges researchers and activists to ask if and how specific struggles share similar grounds, unearth the discur- sive constructions of environment employed in these, explore how they reflect particular features of non-human nature, and examine how they privilege particular claims over others. Why ‘global’? Growing self-awareness and understanding of the global inter- connectedness of human and ecological relations provides new grounds for practices and claims of injustice where the actions of one group of social actors have repercussions on the well-being and security of others. As we begin to appreciate the value of eco- logical resources embedded in everyday forms of economic exchange such as trade, new justice dimensions become apparent whether they relate to material throughout, embedded carbon, or ‘virtual’ water (Martinez-Alier et al., 2010; Zeitoun, 2013). Percep- tions of the ‘planetary character of the ecological crisis’ (Peet et al., 2011b: 10) have justified particular applications of justice rooted in the principle of a single global community or current generation. Such applications become manifested in ideas about the ‘common heritage of mankind’ [sic] with regards to the oceans, Antarctica or rainforests or in notions of ‘common but differentiated responsibil- ity’ in the climate regime (Okereke, 2010). This attention to increasing human and ecological interconnec- tedness does not have to imply any naturalization or fetishization of the global, as highlighted by various contributions to this issue. Nor should it obscure the power relations at play. There is clearly a politics at work in framing responsibilities and rights as global or as falling within the purview of global institutions that seek to acquire for themselves a role in global planetary management (Sachs, 1993). Equally, environmental injustices and claims of jus- tice, Robbins (2014) suggests, arise from locally specific practices due to the unevenness of capitalist development, and only become connected – or global – due to the assembling practices of the actors involved (cf. Holifield et al., 2009). This applies to the pro- duction of injustices as well as the politics of environmental jus- tice. Claims of environmental (in)justice not only operate at a global scale but help to produce a global scale. To some extent awareness of increasing interconnectedness has developed through the global organization of science and knowl- edge about environmental change, leading to the creation of global narratives about processes of environmental change (Buttel and Taylor, 1992; Forsyth, 2003; Leach et al., 2010; Hulme, 2009). Cli- mate change and other discourses affirm the ‘centrality of expert knowledges’ (Peet et al., 2011b: 10), as reflected in the global orga- nization of expertise through bodies such as the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) or the creation of global ‘rosters of experts’: ‘epistemic communities’ (Haas, 1990) conferred a privi- leged and powerful position in global environmental decision- making. Despite the attention given to equity and other justice issues (for example in the latest IPCC Fifth Assessment Report), the central role attributed to particular scientific disciplines raises concerns about the implicit privileging of some ways of knowing over others in knowledge production about the anthropocene (Sikor et al., 2013a). The ascendance of discursive power concen- trated around a few organizations has profound implications for the generation of knowledge about environmental issues, raising issues of ‘cognitive justice’ in the sense of whose knowledge counts: who participates in agenda-setting and to whom are the creators and disseminators of knowledge accountable for the effects of their knowledge (Visvanathan, 2005; Forsyth and Sikor, 2013). Partly in response to the development of epistemic communi- ties and movements mobilizing around global environmental nar- ratives, there has been an enormous proliferation in global governance institutions concerned with the environment. From the Stockholm Conference on the Human Environment in 1972 onwards, global-level institutions have come to exercise oversight over resources key to the livelihoods of the world’s poor whether it be water, seeds, ‘biodiversity’ or, most recently, forests. They have come to establish a ‘particular sort of environmental rule or gov- ernmentality’ (Peet et al., 2011b: 11) through forms of environ- mental neo-liberalism (Goldman, 2005; Heynen et al., 2007). This has taken the form of new forms of private governance that have emerged such as certification schemes for agricultural produce and community forest management which displaces the central role of the state (Li, 2007; Sikor et al., 2013b). Moves to commodify Editorial / Geoforum 54 (2014) 151–157 155 and financialize nature or ‘selling nature to save it’ (McAfee, 1999) in which global institutions broker deals, assure quality and issue pollution or conservation rights (as in carbon trading and REDD respectively) are also indicative of environmental neo-liberalism. While many governance arrangements include provisions for addressing some aspects of justice through appeal or redress mechanisms, there are concerns about the conceptualization and operationalization of justice in such global rule making (Martin et al., 2014; Zeitoun, 2013). These concerns also apply to global and regional trade and investment treaties (such as the EU and NAFTA), even where they have created new arenas for claiming rights and articulating environmental justice claims (Newell, 2007). Another manifestation of globalization, however, is transna- tional forms of mobilization which go beyond site or sector specific mobilizing. Some transnational mobilizations link actors and claims across movements (labor, gender, human rights and envi- ronmental movements) and sites of decision-making (Icaza et al., 2010; Kumar, 2014). The movements often invoke the language of justice together with emphases on rights (rights to water, to food) or the interests of particular groups (forest dwellers, indige- nous groups, etc.) (e.g. Borras et al., 2008; Newell, 2008; Sikor and Stahl, 2011). In this way, they may establish environmental justice as an emergent ‘global brand’ available to environmental activists worldwide, as Agyeman (2014) argues in his contribution to the issue. Nonetheless, the question remains of whether environmen- tal justice offers a framing that is applicable to various sites, given the conflicts between different conceptualizations, as indicated by Mulvaney (2014) or when, as Mehta et al. (2014) suggest, the over- powering influence of local and national political economies may prevent environmental justice from becoming part of a global dis- course that effectively challenges injustices. Thus the ‘global’ in environmental justice emerges through the very practices and pro- cesses that create and contest environmental (in)justices. Globalizing environmental justice It is our impression that the practice of environmental (in)jus- tice has changed in ways which require innovation in the way we seek to account for it and engage with it. There is an urgent need to interrogate the universalizing and globalizing tendencies of environmental justice struggles and examine the concrete scale-making practices and political economic processes which generate environmental (in)justices and underlie environmental struggles. The changing practice of environmental justice and injustice requires a conscious effort to develop research across disciplinary boundaries. Firstly, these globalizing practices and processes require environmental justice scholars and political ecologists to engage with specialists in global environmental politics and inter- national political economy. Those who devote most attention to site or resource specific environmental justice struggles need to develop ways of understanding and explaining the ways in which those struggles are embedded with, and in turn shape broader glo- bal processes. At the same time, analyses of global environmental politics and governance will benefit from greater attention to the local specificity and historical contingency of struggles over resources as they feed into and are influenced by emerging trans- national conventions, treaties, organizations, and networks (Newell and Bumpus, 2012). Secondly, political ecologists and environmental justice schol- ars may also derive mutual benefits from further substantive exchange. Political ecology scholarship is often associated with southern contexts, despite key contributions on the global North (e.g. McCarthy, 2002; Robbins, 2007). Conversely, much environ- mental justice scholarship continues to be shaped by the experi- ences of the global North, despite interest in global movements for climate justice, food justice (e.g., Agyeman et al., 2003; Schlosberg, 2004) and a growing body of scholarship concerned with mobilizations for environmental justice in the global South (e.g., Carruthers, 2008; McDonald, 2002; Walker and Bulkeley, 2006; Walker, 2011). Encounters between political ecologists and environmental justice scholars are still rare, even though the for- mer have begun to explore the use of environmental justice con- ceptions by activists and its utility as an analytical lens (e.g., Schroeder et al., 2008). This themed issue seeks to show how both approaches can be brought into meaningful dialogue with one other and with scholars studying transnational environmental pol- itics and governance. Global environmental justice may also offer new opportunities for collaboration and exchange between engaged scholars and crit- ical activists. It serves as an invitation to engaged scholars for new forms of analysis and to critical activists for new types of action. Attention to global environmental justice in theory and practice thus may offer a platform for engaged scholars and critical activists to learn from one another and support each other’s causes. Engaged research can make important contributions to the practice of global environmental justice through critical analysis. Yet the plurality of justice claims and the inequities of globalized knowl- edge production simultaneously challenge scholars to reflect on their own positionality in relation to the movements they study and whose goals they seek to advance. Acknowledgements We have incurred numerous intellectual debts in pulling this special issue together and developing a program of work on the theme of global environmental justice. Above all, we thank the members of the Global Environmental Justice group at the School of International Development of the University of East Anglia. The group has been very generous in sharing their thoughts, partic- ularly the question of whether and how global environmental jus- tice can become a productive lens to guide research and engagement with practice. We also thank the contributors to this volume and the other participants at our workshop in July 2010. We have learned a lot from all of you (and recognize that the learn- ing isn’t over yet!). Finally, we thank Scott Prudham for the edito- rial support on the themed issue – and setting a fine example of engaged scholarship. References Agyeman, J., 2005. Sustainable Communities and the Challenge of Environmental Justice. New York University Press, New York. Agyeman, J., 2014. Global environmental justice or Le droit au monde? Geoforum 54, 236–238. Agyeman, J., Ogneva-Himmelberger, Y. (Eds.), 2009. Environmental Justice and Sustainability in the Former Soviet Union (Urban and Industrial Environments). MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. Agyeman, J., Bullard, R.D., Evans, B. (Eds.), 2003. Just Sustainabilities: Development in an Unequal World. Earthscan, London. Allen, B., 2003. Uneasy Alchemy: Citizens and Experts in Louisiana’s Chemical Corridor Disputes. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. Anderson, D.G., 2002. Identity and Ecology in Arctic Siberia: The Number One Reindeer Brigade. Oxford University Press, Oxford. Bakker, K., 2003. An Uncooperative Commodity: Privatizing Water in England and Wales. OUP, Oxford. Berry, S., 1993. No Condition is Permanent: The Social Dynamics of Agrarian Change in Sub-Saharan Africa. University of Wisconsin Press, Madison, WI. Blaikie, P., Muldavin, J., 2014. Environmental justice? The story of two projects. Geoforum 54, 226–229. Boelens, R., Cremers, L., Zwarteveen, M. (Eds.), 2011. Justicia Hídrica. Acumulación, Conflicto y Acción Social. Peruvian Institute for Studies, Editorial Fund PUCP, Lima. Bond, P., 2012. Politics of Climate Justice: Paralysis Above, Movement Below. University of KwaZulu-Natal Press, Scottsville. Borras, S.M., Edelman, M., Kay, C. (Eds.), 2008. Transnational agrarian movements: origins and politics, campaigns and impact. Spec. Iss. J. Agrarian Change 8(2–3). http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0005 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0005 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h9000 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h9000 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0020 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0020 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0020 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0015 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0015 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0025 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0025 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0030 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0030 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0035 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0035 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0040 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0040 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h9005 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h9005 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0050 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0050 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0050 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0055 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0055 156 Editorial / Geoforum 54 (2014) 151–157 Bullard, R.D., 2005. The Quest for Environmental Justice: Human Rights and the Politics of Pollution. University of California Press, Berkeley, CA. Buttel, F.H., Taylor, P.J., 1992. Environmental sociology and global environmental change: a critical assessment. Soc. Nat. Resour. 5, 211–230. Campese, J., Sunderland, T., Greiber, T., Oviedo, G. (Eds.), 2009. Rights-based Approaches: Exploring Issues and Opportunities for Conservation. CIFOR and IUCN, Bogor. Carruthers, D. (Ed.), 2008. Environmental Justice in Latin America. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. Chhotray, V., 2014. Disaster relief and the Indian state: lessons for just citizenship. Geoforum 54, 217–225. Cole, L., Foster, S., 2001. From the Ground up: Environmental Racism and the Rise of the Environmental Justice Movement. New York University Press, New York. Dobson, A., 1999. Justice and the Environment: Conceptions of Environmental Sustainability and Theories of Distributive Justice. Oxford University Press, Oxford. Fairhead, J., Leach, M., Scoones, I., 2012. Green grabbing: a new appropriation of nature? Spec. Iss. J. Peasant Stud. 39 (2). Forsyth, T., 2003. Critical Political Ecology: The Politics of Environmental Science. Routledge, London. Forsyth, T., 2014. Climate justice is not just ice. Geoforum 54, 230–232. Forsyth, T., Sikor, T., 2013. Forests, development, and the globalization of justice. Geogr. J. 179 (2), 114–121. Fortmann, L., 1995. Talking claims: discursive strategies in contesting property. World Dev. 23 (6), 1053–1063. Fraser, N., 1997. Justice Interruptus: Critical Reflections on the Post-Socialist Condition. Routledge, London. Fraser, N., 2009. Scales of Justice: Reimagining Political Space in a Globalizing World. Columbia University Press, New York. Goldman, M., 2005. Imperial Nature: The World Bank and Struggles for Social Justice in the Age of Globalization. Yale University Press, New Haven, CO. Gottlieb, R., Joshi, A., 2010. Food Justice. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. Guha, R., 1999. Environmentalism: A Global History. Longman, London. Guha, R., Martinez-Alier, J., 1997. Varieties of Environmentalism: Essays North & South. Earthscan, London. Guha, R., Martinez-Alier, J., 1999. Political ecology, the environmentalism of the poor and the global movement for environmental justice. Kurswechsel 3, 27–40. Haas, P., 1990. Obtaining international environmental protection through epistemic consensus. Millen.: J. Int. Stud. 19 (3), 347–363. Heynen, N., McCarthy, J., Prudham, S., Robbins, P. (Eds.), 2007. Neoliberal Environments: False Promises and Unnatural Consequences. Routledge, London. Hickey, S., Mitlin, D. (Eds.), 2009. Rights-Based Approaches to Development: Exploring the Potential and Pitfalls. Kumarian Press, Sterling, VA. Holifield, R., Porter, M., Walker, G. (Eds.), 2009. Spaces of environmental justice: frameworks for critical engagement. Spec. Iss. Antipode 41(4). Hulme, M., 2009. Why We Disagree About Climate Change: Understanding Controversy, Inaction and Opportunity. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Icaza, R., Newell, P., Saguier, M., 2010. Citizenship and trade governance in the Americas. In: Gaventa, J., Tandon, R. (Eds.), Globalizing Citizens: New Dynamics of Inclusion and Exclusion. Zed Books, London, pp. 163–183. Jasanoff, S., Martello, M.L. (Eds.), 2004. Earthly Politics: Local and Global in Environmental Governance. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. Jones, P., 1994. Rights Issues in Political Theory Series. MacMillan, Basingstoke. Kumar, K., 2014. The sacred mountain: confronting global capital at Niyamgiri. Geoforum 54, 196–206. Larson, A.M., Barry, D., Dahal, G.R., Colfer, C.J.P. (Eds.), 2010. Forests for People: Community Rights and Forest Tenure Reform. Earthscan, London. Leach, M., Scoones, I., Stirling, A., 2010. Dynamic Sustainabilities: Technology, Environment, Social Justice. Earthscan, London. Li, T.M., 2007. Practices of assemblage and community forest management. Econ. Soc. 36, 263–293. Martin, A. (Ed.), 2013. Global environmental in/justice, in practice: introduction. Geogr. J. 179(2), 98–104. Martin, A., McGuire, S., Sullivan, S., 2013. Global environmental justice and biodiversity conservation. Geogr. J. 179 (2), 122–131. Martin, A., Gross-Camp, N., Kebede, B., McGuire, S., Munyarukaza, J., 2014. Whose environmental justice? Exploring local and global perspectives in a payments for ecosystem services scheme in Rwanda. Geoforum 54, 167–177. Martinez-Alier, J., 2002. Environmentalism of the Poor: A Study of Ecological Conflicts and Valuation. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham. Martinez-Alier, J., 2014. The environmentalism of the poor. Geoforum 54, 239–241. Martinez-Alier, J., Kallis, G., Veuthey, S., Walter, M., Temper, L., 2010. Social metabolism, ecological distribution conflicts, and valuation languages. Ecol. Econ. 70 (2), 153–158. McAfee, K., 1999. Selling nature to save it? Biodiversity and green developmentalism. Environ. Plan.: Soc. Space 17, 133–154. McCarthy, J., 2002. First world political ecology: lessons from the wise use movement. Environ. Plan. 34, 1281–1302. McDonald, D. (Ed.), 2002. Environmental Justice in South Africa. Ohio University Press; University of Cape Town Press, Athens, OH; Cape Town. Mehta, L., Allouche, J., Nicol, A., Walnycki, A., 2014. Global environmental justice and the right to water: the case of peri-urban Cochabamba and Delhi. Geoforum 54, 158–166. Movik, S., 2014. A fair share? Perceptions of justice in South Africa’s water allocation reform policy. Geoforum 54, 187–195. Mulvaney, D., 2014. Are green jobs just jobs? Cadmium narratives in the life cycle of Photovoltaics. Geoforum 54, 178–186. Neumann, Roderick P. (Ed)., 2009. Political ecology: theorizing scale. Spec. Iss. Prog. Hum. Geogr. 33(3). Newell, P., 2005. Race, class and the global politics of environmental inequality. Glob. Environ. Polit. 5 (3), 70–93. Newell, P., 2006. Environmental justice movements: taking stock, moving forward. Environ. Polit. 15 (4), 656–660. Newell, P., 2007. Trade and environmental justice in Latin America. New Polit. Econ. 12 (2), 237–259. Newell, P., 2008. Trade and biotechnology in Latin America: democratization, contestation and the politics of mobilization. J. Agrarian Change 8 (2–3), 345– 376. Newell, P., 2012. Globalization and the Environment: Capitalism, Ecology and Power. Polity, Cambridge. Newell, P., Bumpus, A., 2012. The global political ecology of the CDM. Glob. Environ. Polit. 12 (4), 49–68. Newell, P., Wheeler, J. (Eds.), 2006. Rights, Resources and the Politics of Accountability. Zed Books, London. Okanta, I., Douglas, O., 2001. Where Vultures Feast: Shell, Human Rights and Oil in the Niger Delta. Sierra Club, New York. Okereke, C., 2010. Global Justice and Neoliberal Environmental Governance: Sustainable Development, Ethics and International Co-operation. Routledge, London. Okereke, C., Dooley, K., 2009. Principles of justice in proposals and policy approaches to avoided deforestation: towards a post-Kyoto climate agreement. Glob. Environ. Change 20, 82–95. O’Rourke, D., Connolly, S., 2003. Just oil? The distribution of environmental and social impacts of oil production and consumption. Annu. Rev. Environ. Resour. 28, 587–617. Page, E., 2006. Climate Change, Justice and Future Generations. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham. Panitch, L., Gindin, S., 2012. The Making of Global Capitalism. Verso, London. Peet, R., Watts, M. (Eds.), 2004. Liberation Ecologies: Environment, Development, Social Movements, second ed. Routledge, London. Peet, R., Robbins, P., Watts, M. (Eds.), 2011a. Global Political Ecology. Routledge, London and New York. Peet, R., Robbins, P., Watts, M., 2011b. Global nature. In: Peet, R., Robbins, P., Watts, M. (Eds.), Global Political Ecology. Routledge, London and New York, pp. 1–47. Peluso, N.L., 1996. Fruit trees and family trees in an anthropogenic forest: ethics of access, property zones, and environmental change in Indonesia. Comparat. Stud. Soc. Hist. 28, 510–548. Rangan, H., 2004. From Chipko to Uttaranchal: the environment of protest and development in the Indian Himalaya. In: Peet, R., Watts, M. (Eds.), Liberation Ecologies: Environment, Development, Social Movements, second ed. Routledge, London, pp. 371–393. Robbins, P., 2007. Lawn People: How Grasses, Weeds, and Chemicals Make Us Who We Are. Temple University Press. Robbins, P., 2014. Cries along the chain of accumulation. Geoforum 54, 233–235. Sachs, W. (Ed.), 1993. Global Ecology: A New Arena of Political Conflict. Zed Books, London. Sachs, W., Santarius, T. (Eds.), 2005. Fair Future: Resource Conflicts, Security and Global Justice. Zed Books, London. Scanlon, J., Cassar, A., Nemes, N., 2004. Water as a Human Right? IUCN, Gland. Schlosberg, D., 2004. Reconceiving environmental justice: global movements and political theories. Environ. Polit. 13 (3), 517–540. Schlosberg, D., 2007. Defining Environmental Justice: Theories, Movements and Nature. Oxford University Press, Oxford. Schroeder, R., St. Martin, K., Wilson, B., Sen, D. (Eds.), 2008. Third world environmental justice. Spec. Iss. Soc. Nat. Resour. 21(7). Sen, A., 2009. The Idea of Justice. Allen Lane, London. Sikor, T., 2013a. REDD+: the justice effects of technical design. In: Sikor, T. (Ed.), The Justices and Injustices of Ecosystem Services. Earthscan, London, pp. 46–68. Sikor, T. (Ed.), 2013b. The Justices and Injustices of Ecosystem Services. Earthscan, London. Sikor, T., Stahl, J. (Eds.), 2011. Forests and People: Property, Governance, and Human Rights. Earthscan, London. Sikor, T., Stahl, J., Dorondel, S., 2009. Negotiating post-socialist property and state: struggles over forests in Albania and Romania. Develop. Change 40 (1), 171– 193. Sikor, T., Fisher, J., Few, R., Martin, A., Zeitoun, M., 2013a. The justices and injustices of ecosystem services. In: Sikor, T. (Ed.), The Justices and Injustices of Ecosystem Services. Earthscan, London, pp. 187–200. Sikor, T., Auld, G., Bebbington, A.J., Benjaminsen, T.A., Gentry, B.S., Hunsberger, C., Izac, A.-M., Margulis, M., Plieninger, T., Schroeder, H., Upton, C., 2013b. Global land governance: from territory to flow? Curr. Opin. Environ. Sustain. 5, 522– 527. Srinivasan, U.T., Carey, S.P., Hallstein, E., Higgins, P.A.T., Kerr, A.C., Koteen, L.E., Smith, A.B., Watson, R., Harte, J., Norgaard, R.B., 2008. The debt of nations and the distribution of ecological impacts from human activities. PNAS 105 (5), 1768–1773. Upton, C., 2014. The new politics of pastoralism: identity, justice and global activism. Geoforum 54, 207–216. Vincent, A., 1998. Is environmental justice a misnomer? In: Boucher, D., Kelly, P. (Eds.), Social Justice: from Hume to Walzer. Routledge, London, pp. 120–140. http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0065 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0065 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0070 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0070 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0075 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0075 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0075 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0080 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0080 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0600 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0600 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0090 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0090 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0095 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0095 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0095 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0100 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0100 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0105 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0105 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0700 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0115 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0115 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0120 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0120 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0125 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0125 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0130 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0130 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0135 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0135 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0140 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0145 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0150 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0150 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0155 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0155 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0160 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0160 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0165 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0165 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0170 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0170 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0180 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0180 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0185 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0185 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0185 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0190 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0190 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0195 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0705 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0705 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0205 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0205 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0210 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0210 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0215 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0215 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0230 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0230 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0710 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0710 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0710 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0235 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0235 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0715 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0245 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0245 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0245 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0250 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0250 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0255 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0255 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0260 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0260 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0720 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0720 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0720 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0730 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0730 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0735 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0735 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0305 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0305 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0300 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0300 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0295 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0295 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0290 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0290 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0290 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0285 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0285 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0310 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0310 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0315 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0315 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0320 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0320 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0325 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0325 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0325 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0330 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0330 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0330 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0335 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0335 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0335 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0340 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0340 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0345 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0350 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0350 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0355 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0355 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0360 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0360 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0365 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0365 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0365 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0370 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0370 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0370 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0370 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0375 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0375 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0740 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0390 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0390 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0385 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0385 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0395 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0400 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0400 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0405 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0405 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0415 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0420 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0420 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0425 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0425 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0440 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0440 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0445 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0445 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0445 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0430 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0430 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0430 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0435 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0435 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0435 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0435 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0450 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0450 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0450 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0450 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0745 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0745 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0460 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0460 Editorial / Geoforum 54 (2014) 151–157 157 Visvanathan, S., 2005. Knowledge, justice and democracy. In: Leach, M., Scoones, I., Wynne, B. (Eds.), Science and Citizens. Zed Books, London, pp. 83–97. Walker, G., 2009. Globalising environmental justice: the geography and politics of frame contextualisation and evolution. Glob. Soc. Policy 9 (3), 355–382. Walker, G., 2011. Environmental Justice. Routledge, London. Walker, G., Bulkeley, H. (Eds.), 2006. Geographies of environmental justice. Spec. Iss. Geoforum 37(5). White, B., Borras Jr., S.M., Hall, R., Scoones, I., Wolford, W. (Eds.), 2012. The new enclosures: critical perspectives on corporate land deals. Spec. Iss. J. Peasant Stud. 39(3–4). Williams, R., 1999. Environmental injustice in America and its politics of scale. Polit. Geogr. 18 (1), 49–73. Yashar, D., 2005. Contesting Citizenship in Latin America: The Rise of Indigenous Movements and the Post-Liberal Challenge. CUP, Cambridge. Zeitoun, M., 2013. Global environmental justice and international transboundary waters: an initial exploration. Geogr. J. 179 (2), 141–149. Thomas Sikor School of International Development, University of East Anglia, Norwich NR4 7TJ, UK E-mail address: t.sikor@uea.ac.uk Peter Newell Department of International Relations, University of Sussex, Brighton, East Sussex BN1 9SN, UK E-mail addresses: P.J.Newell@sussex.ac.uk Received 21 January 2014 Received in revised form 28 March 2014 Available online 15 May 2014 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0465 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0465 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0470 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0470 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0475 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0490 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0490 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0495 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0495 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0500 http://refhub.elsevier.com/S0016-7185(14)00088-8/h0500 mailto:t.sikor@uea.ac.uk mailto:P.J.Newell@sussex.ac.uk Globalizing environmental justice? Why ‘justice’? Why ‘environmental’? Why ‘global’? Globalizing environmental justice Acknowledgements References work_ioz7gqyyw5fa3l4k4d2bikdszu ---- UvA-DARE is a service provided by the library of the University of Amsterdam (https://dare.uva.nl) UvA-DARE (Digital Academic Repository) Private Law, Regulation, and Justice Hesselink, M.W. DOI 10.2139/ssrn.2744565 10.1111/eulj.12195 Publication date 2016 Document Version Accepted author manuscript Published in European Law Journal Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): Hesselink, M. W. (2016). Private Law, Regulation, and Justice. European Law Journal, 22(5), 681-695. https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2744565, https://doi.org/10.1111/eulj.12195 General rights It is not permitted to download or to forward/distribute the text or part of it without the consent of the author(s) and/or copyright holder(s), other than for strictly personal, individual use, unless the work is under an open content license (like Creative Commons). Disclaimer/Complaints regulations If you believe that digital publication of certain material infringes any of your rights or (privacy) interests, please let the Library know, stating your reasons. In case of a legitimate complaint, the Library will make the material inaccessible and/or remove it from the website. Please Ask the Library: https://uba.uva.nl/en/contact, or a letter to: Library of the University of Amsterdam, Secretariat, Singel 425, 1012 WP Amsterdam, The Netherlands. You will be contacted as soon as possible. Download date:06 Apr 2021 https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2744565 https://doi.org/10.1111/eulj.12195 https://dare.uva.nl/personal/pure/en/publications/private-law-regulation-and-justice(c4a35197-4a87-4760-af63-ac78e0a62d26).html https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2744565 https://doi.org/10.1111/eulj.12195 1 PRIVATE LAW, REGULATION AND JUSTICE Martijn W. Hesselink Abstract: This paper critically engages with the European Regulatory Private Law thesis (ERPL). The main strength of ERPL is that it offers an entirely new perspective on European private law. However, as a complete theory of European private law, ERPL is too one-sided, both from a descriptive and from a normative point of view. With its strong focus on the private law locked up in regulatory silos for specific market sectors it obscures the reality of the consumer acquis and its transformative force. A fuller picture would include the contours of a loosely coherent system of European private law that is currently emerging. The main pillars of that pragmatic system are (for now) the withdrawal rights, unfair terms control, and remedies for non-conformity. Moreover, the contribution of European private law to access justice cannot be the only standard for its evaluation and critique; at least as important are interpersonal justice and democratic legitimacy. Introduction Since 2011, an exciting research project has been based at the European University Institute in Florence. The full title of the project is: ‘European regulatory private law: the transformation of European private law from autonomy to functionalism in competition and regulation’. Its initiator and principal investigator is Hans Micklitz, but it has involved a dozen of other researchers. Together, they have developed what we may refer to as the ‘ERPL-thesis’, or simply as ‘ERPL’. Now that the project is reaching its conclusion, it has invited external comments from colleagues. In this short paper, I will critically engage with the main objectives and central claims of ERPL. The ERPL-project’s aim was to elaborate ‘a normative model of a self-sufficient European private legal order and its interaction with national private law systems’.1 However, the research method it adopted was ‘a socio-legal methodology’, which involved in particular the collection of empirical materials and the incorporation of these into its legal and theoretical analysis.2 Consequentially, I will offer two sets of observations, respectively on ERPL’s descriptive account of European private law, and on its normative model, in particular its conception of justice. As we will see, there is strong a connection between these two, both in the ERPL thesis and in the alternative account that I will propose. I regard two texts as the principal statement (for now) of ERPL, ie A self-sufficient European private law – a viable concept? (2012)3 and European regulatory private law – the paradigms tested (2014).4 These are EUI ‘working papers’ but in reality each of them constitutes an edited volume with a variety of different contributions. In addition, I will also refer to some other publications by the principal investigator where this is helpful for a better understanding of specific ideas underlying ERPL. 1 ‘Project Description’, available at https://blogs.eui.eu/erc-erpl/project-description/. 2 Ibidem. 3 H.-W. Micklitz / Y. Svetiev (eds.), A self-sufficient European private law – a viable concept? EUI Working Papers, LAW 2012/31. 4 H.-W. Micklitz, Y. Svetiev & G. Comparato (eds.), European regulatory private law – the paradigms tested, EUI Working papers, LAW 2014/04. https://blogs.eui.eu/erc-erpl/project-description/ 2 Silos of regulatory private law or pillars of pragmatic private law? The failure of a grand project: chronicle of a death foretold5 The withdrawal in 2014 by the European Commission of its proposal for a regulation on a Common European Sales Law represents a watershed in the development of European private law: the Common Frame of Reference is dead, the dream of a European Civil Code is over.6 That dream (and nightmare for some) had dominated the debate on the future European private law for two decades. At the heart of it was the ambition to substitute the ‘piecemeal’, ‘impressionistic’ or ‘sector-specific’ approach that the EU had taken so far to the Europeanisation of private law with a more systematic approach, based on general rules and more familiar doctrinal concepts of private law. This endeavour was strongly supported by a Europe-wide network of legal academics, who were organised in a variety of projects and were driven by European ideals and by a concern to preserve the systematic nature and doctrinal sophistication of private law systems that had been under constant attacks from unsystematic EU directives, by recreating a systematic private at the European level. The academic movement had gained momentum when it received political endorsement, especially when the European Commission announced in 2003 that a ‘common frame of reference’ was going to be elaborated by academics.7 It reached its apex in 2010 when Viviane Reding, the EU Justice Commissioner and Vice-President of the European Commission, declared the preparation of a European optional instrument on contract law to be the core ambition of her mandate.8 However, very soon it became clear that she had underestimated how much the political climate had changed following the defeat of the European Constitution in referendums in France and the Netherlands, and the implications the revival of nationalist sentiments would have for the political support for this other ‘grand project’. The silos view Regulatory private law Micklitz saw the failure of the ECC/CFR/CESL project coming, well before most others.9 Explicitly as an alternative to that grand project,10 Micklitz and his team set out to map 'European regulatory private law', i.e. the private law resulting from the regulatory agenda of the EU. This 'visible hand of European regulatory private law' marks the transformation of private law into 'economic law'.11 It is one of the greatest merits of ERPL that it makes visible the private law elements in the regulation of a broad variety of markets, in particular 5 After: H.-W. Micklitz and N. Reich, ‘Crónica de una muerte anunciada: the Commission proposal for a ‘Directive on consumer rights’, 46 CMLR (2009), 471-519 6 Proposal for a regulation of the European Parliament and of the Council on a Common European Sales Law, COM(2011) 635 final. The new European Commission withdrew the proposal in December 2014. See Commission Work Programme 2015 A New Start, Strasbourg, 16.12.2014 COM(2014) 910 final, Annex 2, no. 60. 7 A More Coherent European Contract Law, an Action Plan, Brussels, 12.2.2003, COM(2003) 68 final, 62. 8 Cf. V. Reding, 'The next steps towards a European contract law for businesses and consumers, keynote speech at the conference “Towards a European contract law"', Leuven, 3 June 2011 (SPEECH/11/411). 9 H.-W. Micklitz, ‘Failure or ideological preconceptions? Thoughts on two grand projects: the European constitution and the European civil code’, in: K. Tuori and S. Sankari (eds.), The many constitutions of Europe (Ashgate, 2010), 109-142. 10 See H.-W. Micklitz, 'The Visible Hand of European Regulatory Private Law - The Transformation of European Private Law from Autonomy to Functionalism in Competition and Regulation, 28 Yearbook of European Law (2009), 3-59, 6: ‘counter-project’. 11 Micklitz, n 10 above. 3 the new markets resulting from privatisation, e.g. telecommunications, postal services, electricity, gas, transport, health care, education, and from the opening-up of already existing national markets, such as especially the market for financial services. A key element in ERPL’s descriptive account of 'the transformation of private law' is the idea of regulatory silos.12 In a manner akin to systems theory, different market sectors are presented as relatively closed entities, each with its own specific rationality, of which private law rules are but one element. Micklitz and Svetiev write:13 [T]he key markets for services ... may be viewed sectorally, whereby the making of the rules, the substantive standards and the enforcement mechanisms all follow a particular rationality enshrined in that market sector, which cuts across the boundaries of public and private responsibilities as well as boundaries between the national, European and international level. These sectoral regimes could be compared with ‘silos’, in which networks are established, networks between agencies, networks between agencies and industry/business, to some extent public interest groups, networks in which the distinction between public and private, between national and international is withering away.' Clearly, a private law that comes in silos looks radically different not only from what those who believed in a European civil code had in mind, but also from the national private law systems that we have been familiar with in the Member States. For such a private law does not consist of general rules, replaces right and obligations with standards and benchmarks, is made by different actors with different expertise, and is not usually the basis of (nor chiefly meant for) the resolution of individual disputes in courts. If such a private law scattered across a multitude of regulatory silos, each fragment following the regulatory rationale of its respective silo, does represents 'the full picture' of European private law14 then clearly private law has indeed undergone a radical transformation. The question, however, is whether the silos view offers a complete representation of European private law. I don't think it does. The full picture? By placing regulatory silos on the foreground ERPL gives an impression of strong compartmentalisation of European private law according to specific market sectors. However, surely that is only part of the picture. For the silos view almost completely ignores the existence of the consumer acquis. European consumer law does not al all correspond to the model of vertical regulatory silos that each correspond to the specific logic of a particular market sector. Think only of the unfair terms directive, which is applicable - and has been applied - across all sectors of the European internal consumer market, including consumer credit (Cofidis),15 the sale by instalments of encyclopaedias (Océano),16 the sale of parking spaces in a multi-storey car park (Freiburger Kommunalbauten),17 mobile telephone contracts (Mostaza Claro,18 Pannon, 19 Asturcom),20 mortgage loan agreements (Caja de 12 ERPL offers four parameters for the claimed transformation, but the silos element seems to be central to the account. 13 H.-W. Micklitz and Y. Svetiev, 'The transformation(s) of private law', in: n 4 above, 78. 14 H.-W. Micklitz, 'A self-sufficient European private law – a viable concept?', in: n 3 above, 12. 15 Case C-473/00. 16 Joined Cases C-240/98 to C-244/98. 17 Case C-237/02. 18 Case C-168/05. 4 Madrid,21Aziz,22 Sánchez Morcillo and Abril García),23 agreements for a loan to buy a car (Pénzügyi Lízing,24 Banco Español de Crédito),25 insurance contracts (Van Hove),26 and contracts for legal services (Šiba). 27 These are only some examples from CJEU cases; throughout Europe national laws transposing the directive are applied by courts (and are applicable also in the absence of any dispute) to contracts in any thinkable sector of the internal market. In addition, the unfair terms directive, just like the other main European directives constituting the body of European consumer law, also lacks most of the other characteristics that are typical of the regulatory silos, in particular the mix of private law, public law, and private regulation - these directives are essentially concerned with private law -, and the replacement of legislation by standard setting. With little exaggeration we could say that ERPL places on the foreground EU regulation in those fields where the private law aspects are actually of minor importance from the very regulatory perspective ERPL adopts, while it almost completely disregards the EU legislation in which private law is core. The pillars view The consumer acquis A very different descriptive account of European private law can be given, one where European consumer law does not fall off the picture but is in fact at its centre and where consumer law is presented as private law in the more traditional sense of the law determining the rights and obligations of private parties towards one another. Central to this account are the directives that have indeed transformed private law in Europe, i.e. the unfair terms directive 1993,28 the consumer sales directive 1999,29 the consumer rights directive 2011,30 and the 2015 proposals for two new directives on the online sale of goods and of digital content.31 These directives have in common that they are concerned with the rights and obligations of consumers towards their professional sellers and service providers, and that their substantive scope is not limited to any specific market (or to one that is meant to overshadow all others, i.e. the online market). Part of the same transformation are also the consumer credit directive 2008,32 the timeshare directive 2009,33 and the package travel directive 2015,34 which although more sector-specific in scope, share the same horizontal characteristics (notably the private law remedies) while having hardly anything in common with the vertical and closed regulatory silos. 19 Case C‑243/08. 20 Case C‑40/08. 21 Case C‑484/08. 22 Case C-415/11. 23 Case C-169/14. 24 Case C‑137/08. 25 Case C-618/10. 26 Case C‑96/14. 27 Case C‑537/13. 28 Directive 93/13/EEC. 29 Directive 1999/44/EC. 30 Directive 2011/83/EU, replacing Directives 85/577/EEC (doorstep selling) and 97/7/EC (distance selling) 31 Proposal for a directive on certain aspects concerning contracts for the supply of digital content, Brussels, 9.12.2015, COM(2015) 634 final; proposal for a directive on certain aspects concerning contracts for the online and other distance sales of goods Brussels, 9.12.2015, COM(2015) 635 final. 32 Directive 2008/48/EC, replacing 87/102/EEC. 33 Directive 2008/122/EC, replacing Directive 94/47/EC. 34 Directive 2015/2302/EU, replacing Directive 90/314/EEC. 5 Pillars of European private law The replacement in 2015 of the CESL-proposal by two proposals for directives for consumer contract law for the digital single market was a moment of rupture not only because it gave the final blow to the dream of a European civil code,35 but also because it displayed the contours of the developing system of EU private law. What we see emerging today is a loosely coherent system built around three main pillars, i.e. withdrawal rights, unfair terms control, and non-conformity. These are three main categories through which the bulk of disputes between sellers on internal market and their customers are going to be resolved. (There is a fourth characteristic element, but its role is more ornamental: the pre- contractual information duties that are pervasively present but do not do much work in deciding cases as they mostly lack any clear remedies.)36 These pillars of European private law do not formally replace the traditional doctrinal categories of general contract law existing in the Member States, but in practical terms they make them become much less relevant. Withdrawal rights are much easier to handle than the intricate rules on offer and acceptance and the various ‘defects of consent’, each with their nuanced conditions and exceptions. Similarly, the replacement of a good that does not correspond to the contract (either because it does not match the description or it is unfit for its ordinary use) seems more straight-forward than the highly refined and nuanced - and sometimes truly baroque - rules in the Member States concerning the legal consequences of the non-performance of a contractual obligation. And the category of unfair terms, which are simply not binding on consumers, is already overshadowing the operation of classical doctrines like good faith, illicit cause, and (again) the formation rules. In practice, the familiar categories of contract law - sometimes referred to as being based of the life cycle of a contract -, such as formation, validity, interpretation, contents and effects, performance, and non-performance and remedies - that were still the basic categories in the Principles of European contract law, the frontrunner of the European civil code movement -, will be pushed to the background increasingly by withdrawal rights, unfair terms control, and remedies for non-conformity. It is important to realise that these key doctrines soon will apply to most internal market transactions with consumers. Withdrawal rights were introduced by the European legislator for doorstep-selling but were then extended to timesharing, distance selling and consumer credit (and were further synchronised through revisions), and, finally, to all online and off- premise contracts through the consumer rights directive. The control of unfair terms has been applicable in all economic sectors already for more than two decades. As to non- conformity, its scope – already wide under the consumer sales directive – will be further extended, by the proposed new directive, from goods to digital content, i.e. from the retail market to much of the modern economy. In other words, withdrawal rights, unfair terms control, and remedies for non-conformity are where the action is. 35 In theory, the CFR could still become the object of an inter-institutional agreement, as was originally considered to be one of its possible roles. However, at present there does not seem to exist any political support for this idea. Moreover, the academic movement that was the main driver of the CFR seems to have dissolved almost entirely, with perhaps the European Law Institute in Vienna as its last remaining stronghold. 36 The exception are the pre-contractual duties to inform consumers about their withdrawal rights. Violation of that duty has the important legal consequence of extending the term for withdrawal. However, for that reason this may also be regarded simply as one of the situations where a withdrawal right exists. 6 The most striking novelty of the developing three pillar systems is that it is much less sophisticated, nuanced and doctrinal, and much more pragmatic and user-friendly than the familiar private law categories traditionally covering approximately the same legal questions. Thus, they seem to fit much better in a time where states have come to regard their monopolies on the administration of justice (connected with the state monopoly on the legitimate use of force) as a financial burden and, therefore, are massively engaging in the privatisation of dispute resolution by encouraging (or even requiring) sellers (understood in the broad sense of including ‘sellers’ of services) and their customers to resort to ADR and ODR. In these contexts, where sellers and their clients often are not represented by trained lawyers, the niceties of the traditional private law system become a burden, and a more simplified system with a limited set of key doctrines and remedies capable of resolving most disputes becomes more attractive. From the perspective of corrective justice (i.e. the proper determination of the exact borderline between mine and thine, and the correction of illegitimate boundary crossing) and the cultural value of a sophisticated system of private law, this shift undoubtedly represents a major loss. However, from the distributive perspective of the state’s concern to ensure continued equal access to justice (not to be confused with access justice, on which below) this may actually be an acceptable price to pay.37 The personal scope of the three pillar system is limited (formally and for now) to business- to-consumer contracts. For that reason, it may seem improper to speak so generally of pillars of European private law. However, an important ‘radiating’ effect (or even a degree of imperialism) of the developing system of European private law is to be expected for a number of reasons. First, the practical advantage of user-friendliness applies equally to most other than consumer disputes. This is only different in cases where the (financial) stakes are so high that the parties feel they need - in advance of any dispute, when drafting individually the terms of their contract with the assistance of specialised lawyers - the detailed legal certainty than the familiar nuanced system of contract law provides. In all other cases (i.e. the bulk of business-to-business disputes and certainly in the increasingly important peer-to-peer market), dispute resolution costs often represent a decisive factor. Thus, a simplified system of rules for the resolution of disputes concerning market transactions could become an attractive model for lawmakers also outside B2C. Therefore, a certain spill-over effect is to be expected. Moreover, the three pillar system has a very wide territorial scope: it is applicable (indirectly, through transposition and where necessary harmonious interpretation) throughout the entire EU, while the more detailed and nuanced classical contract law doctrines differ from country to country. As a result, while the familiarity of market operators and their legal advisors with the three pillar system will gradually increase they may increasingly regard the deviation from the European private law system for B2B by national legal systems as annoying, thus reversing the grounds of what is experienced as the norm and the exception. Finally, there is the crucial role of the CJEU which represents a strong normalising force of its own. Not only does the CJEU generally ensure the uniform application and interpretation of the European private law system throughout the EU and, crucially, across silos,38 there are three additional reasons why the CJEU is likely to increase public attention for – and hence familiarity with – the emerging 37 On the normative implications of the transformation of private law, see below. 38 In other words, the silos view overlooks the fact that all regulatory silos are connected at the top by the strongly convergent force of the CJEU. 7 main pillars of European private law. First, as a result of the CJEU’s specific task in giving preliminary rulings, cases involving claims of relatively modest economic interest litigated before lower courts, nevertheless reach the Court of Justice. Secondly, the Court has been remarkably activist, and attracting a lot of attention, exactly with regard to these three pillars. Think only of Heininger39 and Messner40 for the withdrawal rights, the long line of cases on unfair terms ranging form Océano to Aziz and beyond, and Quelle41 and Weber and Putz42 for non-conformity. Thirdly, the general style of reasoning of the Court is pragmatic rather than formal-doctrinal. So, the active role of the CJEU in developing the European private law system is likely to further reinforce its pragmatic imprinting and strengthen it divergence from classical private law. The idea of a three pillar system that I am proposing here is not meant as an essentialist theory. Nor should the pillars be reified. In other words, I am not claiming that EU private law is essentially based on three pillars. On the contrary, it is very well possible (indeed quite likely) that in the near future new pillars will be added, with the extension of the substantive scope of EU private law beyond what we traditionally refer to as contract law, or even that such pillars are already emerging, e.g. within the traditional field of tort law (think e.g. of product liability, unfair commercial practices, public procurement, and the private enforcement of competition law).43 However, I would expect that these other pillars would have a similarly pragmatic, undoctrinal nature. In particular, the pillars system does not seem to be based on one single underlying principle (or a limited set of these) that can provide secure guidance in its interpretation and further elaboration.44 A final characteristic – perhaps the most troubling one for those who are committed to preserving the coherence of the national legal system – is that the three pillar system is a competing system of private law. In spite of its instrumental genesis (i.e. internal market building), the right of withdrawal, the non-bindingness of unfair terms, and the remedies in case of non-conformity, are private law doctrines in that they determine the rights and obligations of one private party vis-à-vis another. They may have been enacted with a view to creating a level playing field for sellers and encouraging consumers to shop more often abroad, but they still determine private rights and obligations. However, they do so in a way that is markedly different from the traditional national private law systems, with new concepts (e.g. ‘not binding’ instead of absolute and relative nullity) and remedies (e.g. the withdrawal rights). And as said, for the reasons given, the new system of private law will engage in the competition with the old national ones having a series of comparative advantages. In an influential recent paper, Micklitz compared the German BGB and consumer law, respectively, to a heavy tanker and a sailing boat and argued that ‘[t]he heavy tanker BGB 39 Case C-481/99. 40 C‑489/07. 41 C‑404/06. 42 Joined Cases C-65/09 and C‑87/09. 43 The ‘Acquis principles’ consisted of 7 chapters (in addition to the introductory provisions), on pre- contractual duties, non-discrimination, formation, withdrawal, non-negotiated terms, performance of obligations and remedies. See the Principles of the Existing EC Contract Law (Acquis) Contract I and Contract II, prepared by the Research Group on the Existing EC Private Law (Acquis Group) (Sellier, 2007, 2009). 44 On the normative implications of this, see below. 8 cannot keep up with the dynamics of the agile consumer law.’45 A heavy tanker ship, Micklitz explains, ‘can change its direction in only a limited way and needs time for every change of direction’ while sailing boats ‘can change their direction quickly and easily, but are exposed to wind and weather—that is to say political current—in a far stronger way.’46 This metaphor was inspired, it seems, by the same regulatory perspective as ERPL, where changes in regulatory agendas or techniques are on the foreground. In contrast, from the perspective that I am proposing here the main difference between the classical national systems of private law in the Member States and European private law is not its regulatory nature, but its more pragmatic style. European private law is far less doctrinal and, consequentially, much more user-friendly (for unsophisticated users) and more future-proof than the BGB and other national civil codes, even after their recent reforms. Justice beyond market access Access justice Although the comprehensive mapping of the private law elements in the regulation of different market sectors undoubtedly has been one of its the most important achievements, the ERPL-project’s main objective nevertheless was normative rather than descriptive. The normative model that ERPL proposes is that of ‘access justice’, by which it means justice through market access.47 It is not entirely clear how we are supposed to understand ‘normative’ here. Is ‘access justice’ meant to describe the justice conception of European private law, i.e. the justice understanding immanent to European private law (perhaps as part of its Geist)? Or should we understand ‘access justice’ as an external normative standard by which we can evaluate European private law? The Project Description seems to suggest the former, i.e. access justice as a hypothesis about the normative foundation of European private law, to be verified empirically.48 However, Micklitz has also assimilated access justice to Rawls’ justice as fairness,49 which is meant as an external standard for evaluating whether a society’s main political, social, and economic institutions are sufficiently just.50 Therefore, and also because the normative question of what standards of justice European private law ought to comply with seems to me to be the more important one, in the following I will treat access justice as a theory of justice. From that perspective, I will address three main points with regard to access justice: its ambiguity resulting from its dual normative basis; its disregard for interpersonal justice; and its apparent indifference towards legitimacy. Ensuring market access for the right reasons The European Commission has justified its recent proposals for a consumer contract law for the digital single market by a dual objective, i.e. 1) to boost economic growth in the EU, and 2) to ensure a high level of consumer protection.51 These two objectives are rather different 45 Hans-W. Micklitz, ‘Do Consumers and Businesses Need a New Architecture of Consumer Law? A Thought Provoking Impulse’, Yearbook of European Law, Vol. 32, No. 1 (2013), 266–367, 281. 46 P. 269. 47 See the Project Description, n 1 above. 48 Ibidem, 2: ‘The research, particularly in its empirical dimension, aims to verify some initial hypotheses: (...) 3) ERPL yields its own order of values, enshrined in the concept of access justice.’ See also ibidem, 7-8. 49 Micklitz, n 10 above, 13. 50 J. Rawls, Political liberalism (Columbia University Press, 2005), 11. 51 See Proposal for a directive on certain aspects concerning contracts for the supply of digital content, Brussels, 9.12.2015, COM(2015) 634 final, recitals 1 and 2. 9 in nature. They may go hand in hand when a high level of consumer protection raises consumer confidence and encourages them to reap the full benefits of the internal market. However, they may also conflict, for example when the level or type of consumer protection risks to endanger economic growth, as may happen e.g. when it comes to the protection of particularly vulnerable consumers. The theory of access justice is similarly structured and suffers from the same ambivalence. Access justice means justice through access to markets, in particular through private law rules that make sure that weaker parties obtain and maintain market access. The two key elements are access rights and non-discrimination.52 In this way, one might think, the theory could secure support both from utilitarians and from liberal-egalitarians, albeit for different reasons. Utilitarians will approve of an overall increase in market access because this is likely to bring a rise in social welfare through enhanced preference satisfaction: consumers will be able to buy more goods and services than before (access to more markets) and/or against lower prices (more people have access to the same markets), while sellers will be selling more, which makes them (or their shareholders) happy too. Thus, there is likely to be a net surplus, not only in the narrow sense of GDP growth but probably also in terms of broader notions like preference satisfaction or even happiness.53 The anti-discrimination and anti-exclusion rationale will appeal to liberal-egalitarians.54 If individuals that previously had no access to markets now gain access and, in particular, if these people (or at least some of them) belong to the least well-off groups in society then, for example, from the perspective of the Rawlsian difference principle, which requires from a society making institutional choices with different outcomes for different groups, that these choices work at least also to the benefit of the least well off, insofar the society becomes more just.55 Thus, access justice could be regarded as an implementation through private law of opportunity-egalitarian principles, notably the Rawlsian difference principle.56 At first sight, the capacity to gain support from both welfarists and liberals seems an important advantage of the theory. Indeed, one might think that liberal-egalitarians and utilitarians could reach an overlapping consensus on the principles access justice.57 The idea of an overlapping consensus on political principles of justice was introduced by Rawls in order to address the problem of how to achieve justice in a pluralist society, where people have divergent worldviews and adhere to different ultimate values.58 According to Rawls 52 H.-W. Micklitz, ‘Social justice and access justice in private law’, in H.-W. Micklitz (ed.), The many faces of social justice in private law (Elgar, 2011), 3-60. 53 This would be different only in the case of externalities, which may exist e.g. when more goods bought online are transported over longer distances and the costs of pollution are not internalised through appropriate taxes, but these do not seem to be so pervasive and structural that they provide a general argument against access justice. 54 For some caveats see below. 55 Here I leave to one side the question of whether EU private law rules is part to the basic structure of society to which alone the Rawlsian principles of justice are applicable. On this question, see most recently S. Scheffler, ‘Distributive justice, the basic structure and the place of private law’, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies (2015), 1–23. 56 In this sense, J. Klijnsma, Contract law as fairness (Amsterdam, 2014), 76. 57 In addition, access justice might also appeal to communitarians to the extent that it expresses convincingly (in their eyes) the justice conception immanent to European private law (see above). 58 Rawls, n 50 above. 10 citizens who are willing to live together with mutual respect for each other’s values, should be able to find some common principles of justice that are acceptable from the perspective of their respective worldviews, and could be included by each citizen in her or his ‘comprehensive doctrines’ as a ‘module’. Arguably, access justice would be a good candidate for becoming such a module. However, the notion of an overlapping consensus is problematic. If the principles of justice are to do any useful work they will have to be interpreted. However, different citizens and officials will interpret the principles differently, because, when interpreting, they will seek coherence with the other elements of their respective comprehensive doctrines lying beyond the module. These different worldviews, and their core values, will point in divergent directions. Doing your best to remain neutral does not help since there is no neutral direction.59 Rawls himself underlined that a mere modus vivendi is not sufficient and that the principles will have to be accepted ‘for the right reasons’.60 However, it seems impossible to find an overlapping consensus also with regard to the reasons for adopting the principles of justice. Similar interpretative problems are bound to occur when we try to apply the theory of access justice in practice. The objective of increasing the total amount of market accesses (by opening up more markets to more people) and that of ensuring market access for the least well off (by protecting particularly vulnerable consumers and by combating discrimination) may run parallel up to some point, but when questions arise of whose access should be ensured to which markets and against what price, there is bound to be divergence between the two strands of support for access justice. When that happens – i.e. in hard cases – access justice seems to lack an internal mechanism for answering the question of whether trade-offs are permitted, and if so which. It does not, therefore, seem to represent a stable standard for evaluating – and criticising - the justice of rule choices for European private law that the European legislator has already made in the past or is proposing for the future. Civil justice EU private law offers consumers (and sometimes also other customers)61 certain remedies in certain cases.62 Consumers have these remedies not against the EU, but against the seller or service provider they contracted with. So, as a descriptive matter, even if we understand European private law as regulatory and as aiming at ensuring market access, then still these private law rules at least play a role also in the relationship between a specific buyer and a specific seller. In other words, the interpersonal effects of EU private law are undeniable. If withdrawal rights did not exist, if unfair terms were binding upon consumers, and if no or different remedies were available in the case of non-conformity in consumer sales contracts, then that would matter for the relationships between consumer buyers and 59 For criticism along these lines, J. Waldron, ‘Isolating public reasons’, T. Brooks and M.C. Nussbaum (eds.), Rawls’s Political Liberalism (Columbia University Press, 2015), 113-137. 60 Rawls, n 50 above, xlv. 61 E.g. Regulation (EC) No 261/2004 on air passenger right. 62 To be more precise, EU directives require Member States to attach certain legal consequences, including, in particular, making certain remedies available in certain cases, sometimes as a minimum and sometimes without leaving the Member States any choice to provide consumers with better remedies (and if a Member State fails to do so its private law must be interpreted, as much as possible, as if it did comply with the directive). 11 professional sellers in the EU. Therefore, a theory of justice in European private law that does not address the interpersonal dimension at all would seem to be either a reductive theory or a merely partial one. It is not clear what the theory of access justice is, the former or the latter. As a complete and exhaustive theory of justice in European private law the access justice theory seems seriously flawed, because it totally disregards the interpersonal justice dimension of private law, which includes (but is not limited to) the important corrective (or restorative) justice of correcting or preventing wrongs. The main reason why contract terms should not be binding upon consumers when they cause ‘a significant imbalance in the parties’ rights and obligations arising under the contract, to the detriment of the consumer’,63 is that the enforcement of such terms, except if they have been individually negotiated or are core terms according to the directive,64 would be unjustifiable between the parties. Obviously, the availability of the same minimum level of consumer protection against unfair term throughout Europe is likely also to increase market access. This may contribute to economic growth, which many people regard as a good, and to improving equality of opportunity, which is right from the perspective of opportunity-egalitarian justice. However, it would be absurd to reduce the justice dimension of unfair terms law to mere access justice. The same applies to the strong right to specific performance (repair or replacement) that the consumer sales directive grants consumers in the case of non- conformity: when repair is not possible then the consumer is entitled to full replacement for free even if the costs of replacement are disproportionate to the value of the goods (absolute disproportionality).65 If we want to determine whether that rule, as interpreted by the CJEU, is justifiable then we will also have to address the question whether it is justifiable between the parties (e.g. for the reason that the remedy corrects a wrong; the disproportionate cost could have been avoided by the seller by delivering goods in conformity with the contract); we cannot limit our justification to the - probably correct - observation that the presence of strong remedies for non-conformity is likely to convince more consumers to access the market, especially markets (such as foreign markets) where they think they cannot trust the sellers. The same applies also with regard to the third pillar of European private law that I distinguished above. Undeniably, withdrawal rights play an important instrumental role in increasing consumer confidence in cross-border shopping and they probably contribute to access justice also by encouraging those who would otherwise not dare to shop online. However, this remedy would still lead to an injustice if their exercise by consumers could not be justified towards sellers. As a matter of fact, the justification of withdrawal rights in terms of interpersonal justice is not entirely self-evident. For their striking characteristic is that they allow consumers to walk away from a contract without giving any reasons, which seems to leave open the possibility that they can be exercised also when there are no good reasons.66 One possible justification is that in the type of contracting situations where the law provides for withdrawal rights, the binding force of contract should be understood as in fact postponed until the end of the cooling-off period (which itself can be justified by the concern to prevent a defect of consent resulting 63 Art. 3 Para 1, Directive 93/13/EEC. 64 Arts. 3 Para 1 and 4 Para 2. However, this is a minimum harmonisation directive; the Member States are allowed to provide consumers with more protection. 65 Weber and Putz, n 42 above. 66 That possibility is limited by the CJEU’s subjection of their exercise to the principles of civil law, such as those of good faith or unjust enrichment. See Messner, n 40 above. 12 from a high-pressure situation or from buying on the Internet where one cannot properly see, touch and try the goods). Another one, suggested above, is that given the limited resources that society has for determining the exact private right that parties have, it has opted for a lower (but still acceptable) degree of corrective justice by pragmatically offering more approximate rules and remedies (i.e. withdrawal rights) than the classical nuanced rules on offer/acceptance and defects of consent did – in other words, as a justifiable trade- off in a non-deal world between acceptable degrees of distributive and corrective justice. We do not have to sort out here which justification is more convincing; what matters here is that the mere fact that withdrawal rights boost market access does not suffice as a reason for a seller not to feel wronged by the unilateral and unmotivated withdrawal from the contract by a consumer buyer. In other words, the pillars that I suggested are currently emerging as central to the edifice of European private law will have to be justified also in terms of interpersonal (or civil) justice, as I think they can. The same applies to the more scattered bits and pieces of regulatory private law that ERPL has mapped. As said, it is not clear (to me) whether the access justice theory is meant as a full theory of justice in European private law. If it is not, then it can perhaps still be supplemented by the ERPL-project with an appropriate theory of interpersonal (or civil) justice. Legitimacy As we saw, ERPL makes an empirical case for understanding European private law as disintegrating rapidly into functionally distinct regulatory units (silos) on financial services, transport, energy, telecom and similar, where private law is merely one part, together with public law and self-regulation, of the regulatory compound that is being elaborated across borders by a relatively closed community of highly specialised experts. Above, I questioned, from a descriptive-analytical point of view, whether the silos view represent the full story (or even the most important part of the story) of European private law, and offered an alternative narrative, i.e. the story of a developing pragmatic system of European private law. Now it is time to come back to the silos account and to adopt a normative perspective on this perceived trend towards the fragmentation of private law, and in particular on question of the legitimacy of a private law that comes in regulatory silos. Again, it is not entirely clear whether ERPL is agnostic on the question of legitimacy, limiting itself to a descriptive account, or whether it is in fact also suggesting that it is right that private law making should take place in this way. At times, ERPL seems to endorse the essentially libertarian justification of 'law beyond the state' coming from a normative version of systems theory.67 On this view, democratic legislation belongs to a hopelessly old- fashioned way of looking at the world; what suffices in the globalising world is ‘rough consensus’.68 Similarly, ERPL seems to suggest or imply that the regulatory silo law making practices are not only a reality, but also justified.69 67 G. Teubner, ‘“Global Bukowina”: legal pluralism in the world society’, in: G. Teubner (ed.), Global law without a state (Dartmouth, 1997). 68 See G.-P. Callies and P. Zumbansen, Rough consensus and running code: a theory of transnational private law (Hart Publishing, 2010). 69 See Micklitz and Svetiev, n 12 above, 95. 13 Thus, ERPL seems apologetic or even supportive of practices that from legitimacy point of view, and therefore from the perspective of justice,70 are in fact highly problematic. For the proposition that regulatory silos, where closed communities of technocrats make rules and set standards that will become binding upon others, are also legitimate, is in direct collision with the very basic principle that the addressees of laws, including private laws, should be able to regard themselves also as their authors.71 That principle requires a democratic basis for private law, just as much as for any other legal rule.72 Nor is ‘regulatory private law’ excluded from this legitimacy demand. The determination of both the ends and the means of regulation require a strong democratic basis. From the normative perspective of legitimacy through democracy, therefore, Micklitz’s metaphor of the visible hand is not much more reassuring than Adam Smith’s classic of the invisible hand. First, because ‘hand’ remains in the singular, while market regulation should take place emphatically in the plural, i.e. by all those affected by it together. Secondly, because, while visible hands (in the plural) would at best refer to voting, we should understand the shaping of European private law as a discursive, reason-giving process. In other words, the most adapted anthropomorphic metaphor would seem to be a multitude of speaking mouths. As said, access justice lacks an internal standard for resolving conflicts among its two underlying objectives (i.e. to maximise overall access and to improve access for the least well-off). In addition, as we saw access justice cannot be - and may not be intended as - a full theory of justice. This means that, access justice concerns will have to be reconciled with other justice concerns, including in particular considerations of interpersonal justice. Moreover, although private law has to meet the requirements of justice this does not exclude that other considerations (e.g. of value) may also play a role (to the extent that this is compatible with justice). Further, people differ – sometimes quite strongly - on questions of justice, value and expediency, while we lack direct access to the truth in these matters, if it exists at all (as moral realists believe). Under these circumstances, the question of the proper procedure for arriving at private laws becomes all the more acute. In France, recently citizens were told by presidential decree (‘Le Président de la République ordonne ...’) what their contractual rights and obligations will be as of 1 October 2016.73 Remarkably, there are important differences between the draft ordonnance that was published a year earlier and the final one, but these are not the result of any parliamentary - or otherwise public - debate; they were decided upon behind closed doors at the ministry of justice. In contrast, the bulk of European private law, constituted by the consumer acquis, has a democratic basis. All consumer law directives and regulations have been adopted by the European Parliament, usually after extensive public debates in the Committees for Internal Market and Consumer Affairs and for Legal Affairs and often preceded by public consultations. As a matter of fact, also the Common European Sales Law proposal was adopted, in first reading, by the European Parliament in 2014, after an intense political 70 Normative legitimacy is a dependent concept, i.e. depending on a conception of justice. See R. Forst, Normativität und Macht (Suhrkamp, 2016), 186-197. 71 J. Habermas, Between facts and norms: contributions to a discourse theory of law and democracy (Polity Press, 1996), 408; R. Forst, The right to justification: elements of a constructivist theory of justice (Columbia University Press, 2012), 135. 72 See Habermas, n 71 above. See further M.W. Hesselink, 'Democratic contract law', 11 ERCL (2015), 81-126. 73 Ordonnance no 2016-131 du 10 février 2016 portant réforme du droit des contrats, du régime général et de la preuve des obligations. 14 debate, with several public hearings, culminating in a plenary debate and vote where it carried an overwhelming majority.74 However, it was withdrawn a few months later by the non-elected European Commission following a letter (that was never published) from the Ministers of Justice of five Member States (in none of which the content of the proposed contract law rules had been properly debate in their national parliaments). Of course, I am not suggesting that the democratic basis for the CESL proposal represents an ideal model - much remains to be improved -, but there was a meaningful public (and politicised) debate, not just a vote, while, in contrast, the decision to reject the proposal was taken by technocrats behind closed doors after non-public pressure from national governments. In light of this fact of a democratic European private law (at least to some degree), it seems difficult for a normative theory of European private law to remain agnostic about the need for a democratic basis and, more specifically, the kind of institutions and processes that are needed for European private law to be legitimate. Conclusion The ERPL-project was set up explicitly as a counter-project to the European civil code and common frame of reference project to create a coherent European system of general private law rules. The main strength of ERPL is that it offers an entirely new perspective on European private law (which takes courage) and that it started do so already when everyone else (i.e. politicians and academic) was still concerned mainly with the CFR and the CESL. However, now that the latter project has failed, ERPL looks too one-sided, both from a descriptive and from a normative point of view. With its strong focus on the private law locked up in regulatory silos for specific market sectors and on access justice, it risks to obscure the reality, in particular, of the consumer acquis and its transformative force. A fuller picture, I argued, would include the contours of a developing pragmatic and loosely coherent system of European private law which has the withdrawal rights, unfair terms control, and remedies for non-conformity as its main pillars (for now). That developing system of European private law will have to justified – and can be questioned - in terms not only of its contribution to achieving access justice, but also of its interpersonal justice and democratic legitimacy credentials. 74 European Parliament legislative resolution of 26 February 2014 on the proposal for a regulation of the European Parliament and of the Council on a Common European Sales Law (COM(2011)0635 – C7-0329/2011 – 2011/0284(COD)). Introduction Silos of regulatory private law or pillars of pragmatic private law? The failure of a grand project: chronicle of a death foretold4F The silos view Regulatory private law The full picture? The pillars view The consumer acquis Pillars of European private law Justice beyond market access Access justice Ensuring market access for the right reasons Civil justice Legitimacy Conclusion work_ipdjv6snendojbs2pg44pal2di ---- invalid resource work_ipdo6vkdrjbdxfn44umzdch3vy ---- ethicsmath.DVI Optimality Conditions for Distributive Justice J. N. Hooker Carnegie Mellon University john@hooker.tepper.cmu.edu Abstract We analyze utilitarian and Rawlsian criteria for distribution of limited resources by deriving optimality conditions for ap- propriate optimization problems. We assume that some indi- viduals are more productive than others, so that an inequitable distribution of resources creates greater overall utility. We de- rive conditions under which a distribution of wealth (a) max- imizes utility, (b) maximizes a utility function that accounts for the social cost of inequality, and (c) satisfies a lexmax criterion that reflects the Rawlsian difference principle. We show that a utilitarian solution (a) can distribute resources equally only when all individuals have the same marginal pro- ductivity. Equality is possible under (b) in a diverse popula- tion when the cost of inequality is sufficiently large. Equality is possible under the Rawlsian option (c) when no segment of society has a much greater average productivity than the rest. Equality is more likely to be consistent with Rawlsian justice when there are rapidly decreasing returns to greater investment in productivity, when the most productive indi- viduals are not much more productive than the average, and, ironically, when people are more interested in getting rich. 1 Introduction Utilitarianism and the Rawlsian difference principle imply different criteria for distributive justice, but both can be viewed as mathematical optimization problems. Utilitari- anism maximizes a social utility function whose arguments represent wealth distributed to individuals. The Rawlsian difference principle calls for a lexicographic maximum of the utilities allotted to individuals. This suggests that the theory of optimization might provide some insight into the conditions under which a distribution of wealth satisfies a utilitarian or a Rawlsian criterion. In particular, we use classical optimality conditions to an- alyze distributions over nonidentical individuals. This is a departure from most axiomatic treatments of distributive justice, which assume that individuals are indistinguishable (Blackorby, Bossert, & Donaldson 2002). This capability allows us to study one of the perennial issues of distribu- tive justice—the extent to which an efficient distribution of wealth requires inequality. It is sometimes argued that more utility is created when greater shares of wealth are alloted to The author retains the copyright for this article. individuals who are more talented, more productive, or work harder. We use the modeling device of assigning to each individ- ual i a productivity function ui(α) that measures the total utility eventually created when individual i is initially al- loted wealth α. We then find the distribution of initially available wealth that ultimately results in the greatest to- tal utility. We investigate the degree of inequality that is required to maximize utility, and well as conditions under which a completely egalitarian distribution maximizes util- ity. We perform a similar analysis when the calculation of utility accounts for the fact that excessive inequality may disrupt social harmony and ultimately reduce total utility. In particular, we determine when the cost of inequality is high enough so that an egalitarian distribution maximizes utility. The Rawlsian difference principle states roughly that in- equality should be tolerated only when it is necessary and sufficient to result in greater utility for everyone. We follow the common practice of interpreting this as an imperative to find a lexmax distribution. To do so we suppose that indi- viduals have a common utility function v(α) that measures the personal utility that results when an individual is alloted wealth α. We further suppose that the fraction of the total utility that is eventually enjoyed by an individual is propor- tional to the utility of that individual’s initial wealth allo- cation. Thus we view the initial allocation of resources to individuals as assigning social status and privilege. We de- rive conditions under which a distribution of wealth satisfies the lexmax criterion, as well as conditions under which the lexmax distribution is completely egalitarian. 2 Utilitarian Distribution We first formulate the utilitarian problem. Let the utility generated by person i from wealth xi be ui(xi). If the total resource budget is 1, the problem of distributing wealth to maximize utility is max n∑ i=1 ui(xi) (a) n∑ i=1 xi = 1 (b) xi ≥ 0, all i (c) (1) If we associate Lagrange multiplier λ with the constraint (1b), any optimal solution of (1) in which each xi > 0 must satisfy u′i(xi) − λ = 0, i = 1, . . . , n Eliminating λ yields u′1(x1) = · · · = u ′ n(xn) (2) Thus a wealth distribution is optimal only when the marginal productivity of wealth is the same for everyone. Assume that individuals 1, . . ., n are indexed by increas- ing marginal productivity: u′i+1(α) ≥ u ′ i(α) for all α ≥ 0 and i = 1, . . ., n − 1 (3) In this case, (2) is satisfied only if x1 ≤ · · · ≤ xn. Thus the less productive individuals receive less wealth, as one might expect. Furthermore, a utilitarian distribution is completely egalitarian (x1 = · · · = xn = 1/n) only when the marginal productivities are equal: u′1(1/n) = · · · = u ′ n(1/n) To obtain some idea of how skewed the wealth distribu- tion might be, it is helpful to assume a specific form ui(xi) = cix p i (4) for the utility functions, where p ≥ 0 and each ci ≥ 0. Here ci indicates the productivity of person i. When p = 1, per- son i produces utility in proportion to the wealth received. When 0 < p < 1, greater wealth has decreasing marginal utility, and p = 0 indicates inability to use wealth to cre- ate utility. If individuals are indexed in order of marginal productivity, we have that c1 ≤ · · · ≤ cn. Since an optimal solution of (1) in which each xi > 0 must satisfy (1b) and (2), it is xi = c 1 1−p i   n∑ j=1 c 1 1−p j   −1 (5) when 0 ≤ p < 1. When p ≥ 1, it is clear on inspection that an optimal solution sets xn = 1 and xi = 0 for i = 1, . . . , n − 1. Then the optimal distribution is completely unequal when utility generated is proportional to wealth ( p = 1). The most productive member of society receives all the wealth. The distribution becomes increasingly egalitarian as p ap- proaches zero, reaching in the limit a distribution in which each person i receives wealth in proportion to ci. Thus the most egalitarian distribution that is possible in this utilitarian model is one in which people receive wealth in proportion to their productivity. Moreover, this occurs only in the limiting case when the utility generated is independent of the wealth received (p = 0). When 0 < p ≤ 1, a utilitarian distribution can be completely egalitarian (x1 = · · · = xn) only when c1 = · · · = cn. When p > 1, one individual must receive all the wealth even when c1 = · · · = cn. Using this model, more egalitarian distributions are less efficient. In an optimal distribution with 0 ≤ p < 1, the total utility is ( n∑ i=1 c 1 1−p i )1−p (6) In a completely egalitarian distribution, each xj = 1/n, and the total utility is ( 1 n )p n∑ i=1 ci (7) The ratio (7)/(6) indicates the utility cost of an egalitarian distribution. 3 Cost of Inequality The rudimentary utilitarian model above implies that a utili- tarian solution can result in considerable inequity when indi- viduals have different abilities. A classical defense of utili- tarianism, however, is that excessive inequity generates disu- tility by contributing to social disharmony. The model (1) does not account for any such cost of inequality. A more adequate model may result in utilitarian wealth distributions that are more equitable. A simple way to try to capture the cost of inequity is to model it as a proportional to the total range of incomes. The model (1) becomes max n∑ i=1 ui(xi) − β ( max i {xi} − min i {xi} ) n∑ i=1 xi = 1 xi ≥ 0, all i (8) Presumably, a positive cost factor β could result in utilitarian solutions that distribute wealth more equally. It is also inter- esting to derive how large β must be to result in a completely egalitarian distribution. The analysis is easier if we linearize problem (8) using the following lemma. We again assume that individuals are indexed by increasing marginal productivity, as in (3). Lemma 1 If the utility functions ui satisfy (3), and (8) has an optimal solution, then the following problem has the same optimal value as (8): max n∑ i=1 ui(xi) − β(xn − x1) (a) n∑ i=1 xi = 1 (b) xi ≤ xi+1, i = 1, . . . , n − 1 (c) xi ≥ 0, all i (d) (9) Proof. Let x∗ be an optimal solution of (8) with optimal value U ∗. If x∗j > x ∗ k for some j, k with j < k, then create a new solution x1 defined by x1j = x ∗ k, x 1 k = x ∗ j , and x 1 i = x ∗ i for i 6= j, k. If U1 is the objective function value of solution x1 in (8), then U1 = U ∗ + uj(x ∗ k) − uj (x ∗ j ) + uk(x ∗ j ) − uk(x ∗ k) (10) But due to (3), uk(x ∗ j ) − uk(x ∗ k) ≥ uj(x ∗ j ) − uj(x ∗ k) because j < k. This and (10) imply that U1 ≥ U ∗. Now if x1j > x 1 k for some j, k with j < k, create a new solution x2 in the same manner, and observe again that the objec- tive function of (8) does not decrease. Continue with the sequence x1, . . . , xt until xt1 ≤ · · · ≤ xtn. Then xt is feasi- ble in the problem max n∑ i=1 ui(xi) − β ( max i {xi} − min i {xi} ) n∑ i=1 xi = 1 xi ≤ xi+1, i = 1, . . . , n − 1 xi ≥ 0, all i (11) and has an objective function optimal value no less than U ∗. But (11) has an optimal value no greater than U ∗ because it is more highly constrained than (8). Thus (8) and (11) have the same optimal value. But (11) is obviously equivalent to (9), which implies that (8) and (9) have the same optimal value, as claimed. To characterize optimal solutions of (9), we associate La- grange multiplier λ with (9b) and multipliers µ1, . . . , µn−1 with the constraints in (9c). The Karush-Kuhn-Tucker (KKT) optimality conditions imply that x is optimal in (9) only if there are a value of λ and nonnegative values of µ1, . . ., µn−1 such that u′1(x1) + β − λ − µ1 = 0 u′i(xi) − λ + µi−1 − µi = 0, i = 2, . . . , n − 1 u′n(xn) − β − λ + µn−1 = 0 (12) where µi = 0 if xi < xi+1 in the solution. We first examine the case in which each individual re- ceives a different wealth allotment xi. In this case each µi = 0, and we can eliminate λ from (12) to obtain u′2(x2) = · · · = u′n−1(xn−1) u′1(x1) = u ′ 2(x2) − β u′n(xn) = u ′ 2(x2) + β Thus all individuals who are not at the extremes of the distri- bution have equal marginal productivity in a utilitarian dis- tribution, just as they do in the solution of the original model (1). The individual at the bottom of the distribution, how- ever, has marginal productivity that is β smaller than that of those in the middle, while the individual at the top has marginal productivity that is β larger than that of those in the middle. This tends to result in somewhat larger allotment for the individual at the bottom, and a smaller allotment for the one at the top. Since the remaining individuals are forced to lie between these extremes, the net result is a distribution that is less skewed than in the original model. 4 Equality in a Utilitarian Distribution We can also determine what value of β results in a com- pletely egalitarian model. In this case the multipliers µi can be nonzero. Again eliminating λ from the KKT conditions (12), we get 2µ1 − µ2 = d1 µ1 + µi − µi+1 = di, i = 2, . . . n − 2 µ1 + µn−1 = dn−1 (13) where di = u′1(x1) − u ′ i+1(xi+1) + β, i = 1, . . ., n − 1 dn−1 = u′1(x1) − u ′ n(xn) + 2β (14) It can be checked that the following solves (13) µk = k n n−1∑ i=k di − ( 1 − k n )k−1∑ i=1 di (15) for k = 1, . . . , n − 1. Substituting (14) into (15), we get µk = β + ( 1 − k n ) k∑ i=1 u′i(xi) − k n m∑ i=k+1 u′i(xi) (16) for k = 1, . . . , n − 1. We now consider an egalitarian solution, in which each xi = 1/n. Since each µi ≥ 0 in an optimal solution, we obtain the following from (16). Theorem 2 Suppose that individuals are indexed in order of increasing marginal productivity. Then an utilitarian dis- tribution in the model (8) is egalitarian ( x1 = · · · = xn) only if β ≥ k n m∑ i=k+1 u′i(1/n) − ( 1 − k n ) k∑ i=1 u′i(1/n) (17) for k = 1, . . . , n − 1. This may be easier to interpret for the specific productiv- ity functions defined earlier. Corollary 3 If the productivity function ui are given by (4), a utilitarian distribution in the model (8) is egalitarian only if β ≥ p np k(n − k) ( 1 n − k n∑ i=k+1 ci − 1 k k∑ i=1 ci ) for k = 1, . . . , n − 1. Thus to determine the minimum β required to ensure equality, we examine each group of k smallest coefficients c1, . . . , ck. The value of β depends on the difference be- tween the average of these coefficients and the average of the remaining coefficients. Thus if there is a group of individ- uals who are much less productive on the average than the remaining individuals, relative to the overall range of pro- ductivities, a larger β is required to ensure inequality. This could occur in a two-class society with a relatively homoge- neous underclass and relatively homogenous elites, for ex- ample. 5 Rawlsian Distribution A lexmax (lexicographic maximum) model can be used to represent a wealth distribution that satisfies the Rawlsian difference principle. As before we let ui(xi) be the social utility generated by a person i who initially receives wealth xi. We also suppose that the fraction of total utility received by person i is proportion to the personal utility v(xi) of per- son i’s initial wealth allocation. Thus everyone has the same personal utility function, even though different people may have different productivity functions. If yi is the utility enjoyed by person i, any solution of the following problem is a Rawlsian distribution: lexmax y (a) yi y1 = v(xi) v(x1) , i = 2, . . . , n (b) n∑ i=1 yi = n∑ i=1 ui(xi) (c) n∑ i=1 xi = 1 (d) xi ≥ 0, i = 1, . . . , n (e) (18) where y = (y1, . . . , yn). By definition, y∗ solves (18) if and only if y∗i solves problems L1, . . . , Ln, where Lk is the problem max min {yk, . . . , yn} (y1, . . ., yk−1) = (y∗1 , . . ., y ∗ k−1) (18b)–(18e) (19) The lexmax solution is frequently defined with respect to a particular ordering y1, . . . , yn of the variables, in which case L1 maximizes yk rather than min{yk, . . ., yn}. This is inappropriate for the Rawlsian problem because we do not know in advance how the solution values y∗k will rank in size. Suppose, however, that persons 1, . . . , n are indexed by increasing marginal productivity as in (3). Then we can assume without loss of generality that persons with less marginal productivity are nearer the bottom of the distribu- tion. Lemma 4 Suppose that (3) holds and that v(α) is monotone nondecreasing for α ≥ 0. Then if (18) has a solution, it has a solution in which y1 ≤ · · · ≤ yn. Proof. Since v is monotone, it suffices to show that (18) has a solution (x̄, ȳ) in which x̄1 ≤ · · · ≤ x̄n. For this it suffices to exhibit a solution (x̄, ȳ) that solves Lk for k = 1, . . . , n and for which x̄1 ≤ · · · ≤ x̄n. Let (x∗, y∗) be a solution of (18), and let (x0, y0) = (x∗, y∗). If x01 ≤ x 0 i for i = 2, . . . , n, then x 0 solves L1 and we let x1 = x0. Otherwise we suppose x0k = mini{x 0 i } and define x1 by x11 = x 0 k, x 1 k = x 0 1, and x 1 i = x 0 i for i 6= 1, k. We define y1 to satisfy (18b)-(18c). We can see as follows that (x1, y1) solves L1. If U0 = ∑ i ui(xi) is the total utility for solution (x0, y0), then the total utility for solution (x1, y1) is U1 = U0 + uk(x 0 1) − uk(x 0 k) + u1(x 0 k) − u1(x 0 1) But we have from (3) that uk(x 0 1) − u1(x 0 k) ≥ u1(x 0 1) − u1(x 0 k) Thus U1 ≥ U0, and x1 generates no less total utility than x0. Since utility is allotted to the y1i s in proportion to v(x 1 i ), and v is monotone nonincreasing, we get y11 ≤ y01. Thus (x1, y1) solves L1. Now if x11 ≤ x 1 i for i = 2, . . . , n, then (x 1, y1) solves L1, L2 and we let (x2, y2) = (x1, y1). Otherwise we sup- pose x1k = mini≥2{x 1 i } and define x 2 by x21 = x 1 k , x 2 k = x 1 1, and x2i = x 1 i for i > 2 and i 6= k. We can show as above that (x2, y2) solves L1, L2. In this fashion we construct the sequence (x1, y1), . . . , (xn, yn) and let (x̄, ȳ) = (xn, yn). By construction, x̄1 ≤ · · · ≤ x̄n. Since (x̄, ȳ) solves L1, . . . , Ln, it solves (18). To analyze solutions of (18), it is convenient to eliminate the variables yi from each Lk . Using constraints (18b)– (18c), we get yi = v(xi) n∑ i=1 ui(xi) n∑ i=1 v(xi) , i = 1, . . ., n Using Lemma 4, Lk can be written max v(xk) n∑ i=1 ui(xi) n∑ i=1 v(xi) (a) (x1, . . . , xk−1) = (x∗1, . . ., x ∗ k−1) (b) n∑ i=1 xi = 1 (c) xk ≤ · · · ≤ xn (d) xk ≥ 0 (e) (20) where x∗1, . . . , x ∗ k−1 are previously computed solutions of L1, . . . , Lk−1, respectively. We focus first on L1. Associating Lagrange multipliers µ1, . . . , µn−1 with the constraints in (20d), the KKT opti- mality conditions imply that a solution x with each xi > 0 is optimal in (20) only if there are nonnegative values of µ1, . . . , µn−1 such that v′(x1) Σu Σv + v(x1) u′1(x1)Σv − v′(x1)Σu (Σv)2 − λ − µ1 = 0 v(x1) u′i(xi)Σv − v′(xi)Σu (Σv)2 − λ + µi−1 − µi = 0, i = 2, . . . , n − 1 v(x1) u′n(xn)Σv − v′(xn)Σu (Σv)2 − λ + µn−1 = 0 (21) where Σu = n∑ i=1 ciui(xi), Σv = n∑ i=1 v(xi) and where µi = 0 if xi < xi+1 in the solution. We begin by examining the case in which each individual receives a different allotment xi. Here each µi = 0, and (21) implies v′(x1) v(x1) + u′1(x1) Σu − v′1(x1) Σv = u′i(xi) Σu − v′i(xi) Σv for i = 1, . . . , n−1, assuming v(x1) > 0. This says that the marginal difference between productivity and personal util- ity is the same for everyone except the lowest ranked indi- vidual, for whom the difference is somewhat less. This tends to increase the allotment to the lowest individual, reducing the gap between this person and the others. The optimal- ity conditions for L2 are similar and likewise move the sec- ond closest individual closer to those who are more highly ranked. Thus in general, the lexmax solution results in a distribution that is more egalitarian than one in which the marginal difference between productivity and personal util- ity is the same for everyone. 6 Equality in a Rawlsian Distribution We now examine conditions under which a Rawlsian dis- tribution can be egalitarian. We found earlier that a util- itarian distribution with utility functions ui(xi) = cix p i , v(xi) = x q i cannot be egalitarian unless individuals are iden- tical in their productivity. We will show that a Rawlsian dis- tribution can, under certain conditions, be egalitarian in a more diverse population. In an egalitarian distribution any µi can be nonzero. We eliminate λ from the optimality conditions (21) for L1 to obtain v′(x1) v(x1) + u′1(x1) Σu − v′(x1) Σv − 1 v(x1) Σv Σu µ1 = u′i(xi) Σu − v′(xi) Σv + 1 v(x1) Σv Σu (µi−1 − µi) (22) ‘ for i = 2, . . ., n − 1, and v′(x1) v(x1) + u′1(x1) Σu − v′(x1) Σv − 1 v(x1) Σv Σu µ1 = u′n(xn) Σu − v′(xn) Σv + 1 v(x1) Σv Σu µn−1 (23) This yields the following. Theorem 5 Suppose the productivity functions are given by ui(α) = ciαp and the utility function by v(α) = αq. Then L1 has an egalitarian solution ( x1 = · · · = xn) only if 1 k k∑ i=1 ci ≥ 1 n − k n∑ i=k+1 ci − q p · n − k k n∑ i=1 ci (24) or equivalently, 1 k k∑ i=1 ( 1 + q p · n − k k ) ci ≥ 1 n − k n∑ i=k+1 ( 1 − q p · n − k k ) ci (25) for k = 1, . . . , n − 1. Proof. The equations (22)–(23) can be written as (13) where di = v(x1) Σu Σv ( v′(x1) v(x1) − u′i+1(xi+1) − u′1(x1) Σu + v′(xi+1) − v′(x1) Σv ) for i = 1, . . . , n − 1. Substituting x1 = · · · = xn = 1/n and the functions ui, v as given above, we obtain di = qn −p n∑ j=1 cj − pn−p (ci+1 − c1) (26) Since (15) solves (13), we can substitute (26) into (15) and get µk = p k(n − k) n1+p ( q pk n∑ i=1 ci + 1 k k∑ i=1 ci − 1 n − k n∑ i=k+1 ci ) for k = 1, . . ., n − 1. The KKT conditions imply that xk = · · · = xn = 1/n can be an optimal solution only if µk ≥ 0 for k = 1, . . . , n − 1, which implies (24). An egalitarian solution (x1 = · · · = xn) solves L1 if and only if it solves the lexmax problem (18). If it solves L1, then a lexmax solution must have x1 = 1/n, which implies by (18d) that x2 = · · · = xn = 1/n. If an egalitarian solution does not solve L1, then some distribution with x1 < 1/n solves L1, which implies that x1 < 1/n in any lexmax solution. Thus we have Corollary 6 If the productivity functions are given by ui(α) = ciαp and the utility function by v(α) = αq, then a lexmax distribution is egalitarian ( x1 = · · · = xn) only if (24) and (25) hold. Thus a Rawlsian distribution is completely egalitarian when the gap between the average productivity of the k least productive individuals and that of the remaining population is not too great for any k. The maximum gap is proportional to q/p and (n − k)/k. This means that a smaller gap is re- quired when the marginal utility of wealth decreases rapidly with the level of wealth (q is small), and when the opposite is true of marginal productivity ( p is large). Thus an inegal- itarian distribution is more likely when individuals do not care very much about getting rich and are satisfied with a moderate level of prosperity. Inequality is also more likely when allocating greater advantages to talented or industrious people reaps consistently greater rewards. An egalitarian distribution also requires a smaller produc- tivity gap between the highest class and the remaining pop- ulation (i.e., when k = n−1 ) than between the lowest class and the remaining population ( k = 1). Thus if the distribu- tion of talents and industry has a long tail at the upper end, as is commonly supposed, the condition for equality could be hard to meet. 7 Conclusion We find that a utilitarian distribution of wealth can result in substantial inequality when some individuals are more pro- ductive than others. The distribution is completely egali- tarian only when every individual has the same marginal productivity. When marginal productivities are unequal, the most egalitarian distribution that is possible is one in which individuals are allocated wealth in proportion to their marginal productivity, and this occurs only when there are rapidly decreasing marginal returns for greater allocations of wealth. A more egalitarian distribution results when the utility function includes a penalty to account for social dysfunc- tion that inequality may cause. In particular, if the penalty is proportional to the gap between the richest and poorest individuals, we can calculate a constant of proportionality that results in a completely egalitarian distribution. This constant tends to be larger when there is large gap in av- erage productivity between two segments of society. That is, there a group of individuals that have a much smaller average marginal productivity than the remaining individu- als, relative to the overal range of productivities. This may occur, for example, when elites and common people form fairly homogenous groups separated by a large gap in aver- age productivity. Finally, the Rawlsian difference principle can result in a completely egalitarian distribution when no two segments of society have a large gap in average productivity. Equality is more likely to occur when there are decreasing returns for placing greater investment in talented and industrious people. Somewhat surprisingly, equality is also more likely when people are nearly as concerned about getting rich as about living a minimally comfortable lifestyle. When people want riches more, a privileged class is less likely to be con- sistent with Rawlsian justice. Finally, equality is more likely when the most talented and industrious individuals are not much more productive than the average person, even though the least productive individuals may fall far below the mean. References Blackorby, C.; Bossert, W.; and Donaldson, D. 2002. Util- itarianism and the theory of justice. In Arrow, K.; Sen, A.; and Suzumura, K., eds., Handbook of Social Choice and Welfare, Vol. 1, volume 19 of Handbooks in Economics. Amsterdam: Elsevier. 543–596. Bouveret, S., and Lemaitre. 2006. Finding leximin-optimal solutions using constraint programming: New algorithms and their application to combinatorial auctions. In Endriss, U., and Lang, J., eds., 1st International Workshop on Com- putational Social Choice . Isermann, H. 1982. Linear lexicographic optimization. OR Spektrum 123:223–228. work_ipr47rpk6jdfdhcr5ftvl664wq ---- In 2007/08 the crime most commonly recorded by police in England and Wales (36 per cent) and Scotland (33 per cent) was theft and handling stolen goods. In Northern Ireland it was criminal damage (28 per cent). (Table 9.1) Between 2006/07 and 2007/08 there was a 10 per cent decrease in the incidence of crime measured by the British Crime Survey (BCS) in England and Wales, from 11.3 million to 10.1 million crimes. (Figure 9.2) Violent crime, which comprises assault with or without injury, wounding and robbery, accounted for one-fifth (2.2 million incidents) of all BCS crime in England and Wales in 2007/08. (Table 9.3) In 2006, 26 per cent of ten to 25-year-olds in England and Wales were victims of personal crime in the last 12 months, including robbery, personal theft and assault (either with or without injury). (Table 9.4) In 2007/08 there were 17,300 crimes reported to the police in England and Wales in which a firearm was used, a 6 per cent decrease from 2006/07. (Figure 9.7) Of offenders aged 18 and over leaving prison or starting a community sentence in England and Wales in the first quarter of 2006, 39 per cent reoffended within one year, the lowest reoffending rate since the series began. (Page 136) C h ap ter 9 Download data by clicking the online pdf www.statistics.gov.uk/ socialtrends39 Crime and justice Chapter 9: Crime and justice Social Trends 39: 2009 edition 128 9 Crime can affect anyone, regardless of whether or not they have been a victim. In addition to suffering or loss resulting directly from crime, people may be affected by their perceptions of changing crime levels and their fear of crime may affect the way they live their daily lives. Dealing with crime and associated problems is an ever-present concern for society and the Government. There are two main sources of crime statistics: police-recorded crime and household population surveys of crime (see Measures of crime text box). Crime levels This chapter discusses both the incidence and prevalence of crime (see Appendix, Part 9: Prevalence rates and incidence rates). The incidence of crime, defined as the number of crimes that have taken place, is analysed in this section. The prevalence of crime, or the proportion of people who were victims, is covered in the Offences and victims section later in the chapter. Following the introduction of the National Crime Recording Standard (NCRS) in England and Wales in 2002 (see Appendix, Part 9: National Crime Recording Standard) there was an overall increase in the number of crimes recorded by the police that year, with less serious crimes, including criminal damage, minor theft and assault without injury, increasing the most. The introduction of the Scottish Crime Recording Standard (SCRS) in April 2004 resulted in similar increases in the number of less serious crimes recorded by the police in Scotland. In 2007/08 around 5.5 million crimes were recorded by the police across the UK (Table 9.1). Nearly three-quarters (72 per cent) of recorded crimes in England and Wales were property crimes; these include theft and handling stolen goods, burglary, criminal damage, and fraud and forgery. Violence against the person accounted for around one-fifth (19 per cent) of all recorded crime in England and Wales, the same proportion as in 2006/07. Measures of crime There are two main measures of the extent of crime in the UK: surveys of the public, and crime recorded by the police. The British Crime Survey (BCS) interviews adults aged 16 and over who are living in private households in England and Wales. The Scottish Crime and Victimisation Survey (SCVS) and the Northern Ireland Crime Survey (NICS) interview adults aged 16 and over in Scotland and Northern Ireland respectively. In some ways the BCS, the SCVS and the NICS give a better measure of many types of crime than police- recorded crime statistics. These surveys show the large number of offences that are not reported to the police and also give a more reliable picture of trends, as they are not affected by changes in levels of reporting to the police or by variations in police recording practice (see Appendix, Part 9: Types of offence in England and Wales, in Scotland, and in Northern Ireland). Recorded crime data cover offences reported to and recorded by the police. The National Crime Recording Standard (NCRS), introduced in England and Wales in 2002 and the Scottish Crime Recording Standard (SCRS), introduced in 2004, were implemented with the aim of taking a more victim-centred approach and providing consistency between police forces (see Appendix, Part 9: National Crime Recording Standard). Police-recorded crime and survey-measured crime have different coverage. Unlike crime data recorded by the police, surveys are generally restricted to crimes against adults living in private households and their property and do not include some types of crime (for example, fraud, murder and victimless crimes such as drug use, where there is not a direct victim). See also Appendix, Part 9: Availability and comparability of data from constituent countries. Table 9.1 Crimes recorded by the police: by type of offence,1 2007/08 United Kingdom Percentages England & Wales Scotland Northern Ireland Theft and handling stolen goods 36 33 23 Theft from vehicles 9 4 3 Theft of vehicles 3 3 3 Criminal damage 21 31 28 Violence against the person2 19 3 27 Burglary 12 7 11 Drugs offences 5 11 3 Fraud and forgery 3 2 3 Robbery 2 1 1 Sexual offences 1 1 2 Other offences3 1 12 3 All notifiable offences (=100%) (thousands) 4,951 386 108 1 See Appendix, Part 9: Types of offence in England and Wales, in Scotland, and in Northern Ireland, and Availability and comparability of data from constituent countries. 2 Data for Scotland are serious assaults only. Those for England and Wales and Northern Ireland are all assaults including those that cause no physical injury. 3 Northern Ireland includes ‘offences against the state’. Scotland excludes ‘offending while on bail’. Source: Home Office; Scottish Government; Police Service of Northern Ireland Social Trends 39: 2009 edition Chapter 9: Crime and justice 129 9 The definition of crime in Northern Ireland is broadly comparable with that used in England and Wales. In 2007/08 the police in Northern Ireland recorded 108,000 crimes, nearly two-thirds (65 per cent) of which were property crimes. More than one-quarter (27 per cent) of recorded crime in Northern Ireland involved violence against the person, again showing little change from 2006/07. In Scotland the term ‘crime’ is reserved for the more serious offences, broadly equivalent to ‘indictable’ and ‘triable-either- way’ offences in England and Wales, while less serious crimes are called ‘offences’ (see Appendix, Part 9: Availability and comparability of data from constituent countries). In 2007/08, 386,000 crimes were recorded by the police in Scotland. The most common recorded crime in Scotland was theft and handling stolen goods (33 per cent), followed by criminal damage (31 per cent), unchanged from 2006/07. The number of crimes recorded by the police tends to be lower than that reported by household surveys, largely because survey respondents identify a large number of offences that have not been reported to the police. Based on the 2007/08 British Crime Survey (BCS), 42 per cent of incidents of BCS comparable crime in England and Wales, that is crimes where BCS data can be directly compared with police statistics (see Appendix, Part 9: Comparable crimes), were reported to the police, or became known to the police by some other means. Victims gave a variety of reasons for not reporting crime to the police, with the most common being that they felt the crime was too trivial, there was no loss or that in their view the police would not, or could not, do anything about it. The incidence of crime estimated by the BCS in England and Wales rose steadily throughout the 1980s and early 1990s and peaked in 1995, at 19.4 million offences. There was then a steady decline and the level remained relatively stable between 2004/05 and 2006/07. However, between 2006/07 and 2007/08 there was a 10 per cent decrease in the incidence of BCS crime, from 11.3 million to 10.1 million crimes and the level of crime in 2007/08 was almost one-half the level in the peak year of 1995 (Figure 9.2). The Northern Ireland Crime Survey (NICS) estimated that 199,000 crimes were committed against adults living in private households in the 12 months prior to interview in 2007/08. This was an increase from 195,000 crimes identified in 2006/07, but still much lower than the 295,000 identified in the 2003/04 NICS. Because there was no Scottish Crime and Victimisation Survey (SCVS) in 2007, the most recent available data for Scotland are for 2005/06. The survey estimated that around 1.1 million crimes were committed against adults in private households in the 12 months prior to interview in 2005/06, an increase from 900,000 in 2003/04. The incidence of SCVS crime in 2005/06 was at the same level it was in 1992. Of the 10.1 million crimes reported by the BCS in England and Wales in 2007/08, almost two-thirds (6.4 million) were household crimes and more than one-third (3.7 million) were personal crimes (Table 9.3 overleaf). There was an overall reduction in the incidence of both types of crime reported in 2007/08. The most common crime reported, accounting for more than one-quarter of all BCS crime, was vandalism, with an estimated 2.7 million incidents experienced in the 12 months prior to interview. This was the most commonly experienced household crime each year since 2001/02, but during the 1990s vehicle theft was the most common, ranging from 3.5 million to 4.4 million crimes. Violent crime, which comprises assault with or without injury, wounding and robbery, accounted for one-fifth (2.2 million incidents) of all BCS crime reported in 2007/08. Offences and victims The likelihood of being a victim of crime varies according to where you live. The highest levels of household crime in England and Wales according to the 2007/08 British Crime Survey (BCS), including theft of, or from, vehicles, bicycle theft, household theft, burglary, and vandalism, were experienced by those living in Yorkshire and the Humber where one-fifth (20 per cent) of households reported being a victim once or more in the 12 months prior to interview. The North East Figure 9.2 British Crime Survey offences1 England & Wales Millions 0 5 10 15 20 1993 1995 1997 1999 2001/02 2003/04 2005/06 2006/07 2007/08 1 Until 2000, respondents were asked to recall their experience of crime in the previous calendar year. From 2001/02 onwards the British Crime Survey became a continuous survey and the recall period was changed to the 12 months prior to interview. Source: British Crime Survey, Home Office Chapter 9: Crime and justice Social Trends 39: 2009 edition 130 9 (19 per cent) and the North West (18 per cent) had the next highest incidence of household crime. The lowest incidence was reported by those living in the South West (14 per cent). There are also differences in the characteristics of those households more at risk and this varies by the type of crime. For example, households with no security measures were more than ten times as likely than average to be victims of burglary according to the 2007/08 BCS, and households headed by someone aged 16 to 24 were three times more likely than average to be burgled. The highest rate of personal crime, including assault, sexual offences, robbery, theft from the person and other personal theft, was experienced by those living in London, with 8 per cent having been victims in the 12 months prior to interview. The areas with the lowest risk of personal crime were Wales and the South West, at 5 per cent each. Risk of personal crime also varied according to the characteristics of the victim. Men and women aged 16 to 24 were more likely to have experienced a violent offence than those in any other age group. The risk for young men was more than double that for young women (13 per cent compared with 6 per cent) and although the difference declined with age, men of all ages were more likely than women to have experienced a violent offence. The risk of being a victim of violence had decreased to less than 1 per cent by the age of 55 for women and age 65 for men. The incidence of personal crime continues to be high among young people aged under 26. The 2006 Offending, Crime and Justice Survey (OCJS) reported that 12 per cent of ten to 25-year-olds had experienced at least one incident of personal theft in England and Wales in the 12 months prior to interview (Table 9.4). More than one-quarter (26 per cent) were victims of some kind of personal crime over the same period, including robbery, personal theft and assault (either with or without injury). Young males were more likely than young females to be victims of a personal crime within the last 12 months (31 per cent compared with 21 per cent). The difference was most pronounced among ten to 15-year-olds; nearly two-fifths (38 per cent) of boys of this age group were victims compared with around one-fifth (22 per cent) of girls. Table 9.3 Incidents of crime: by type of offence1 England & Wales Millions 1981 1991 1995 2001/02 2005/06 2006/07 2007/08 Household crime Vandalism 2.7 2.8 3.4 2.6 2.7 2.9 2.7 All vehicle-related theft2 1.8 3.8 4.4 2.5 1.7 1.7 1.5 Burglary 0.7 1.4 1.8 1.0 0.7 0.7 0.7 Bicycle theft 0.2 0.6 0.7 0.4 0.4 0.5 0.4 Other household theft3 1.5 1.9 2.3 1.4 1.2 1.2 1.1 All household crime 6.9 10.4 12.4 7.9 6.8 7.1 6.4 Personal crime Theft from the person 0.4 0.4 0.7 0.6 0.6 0.6 0.6 Other thefts of personal property 1.6 1.7 2.1 1.4 1.2 1.1 1.0 All BCS violence 2.1 2.6 4.2 2.7 2.3 2.5 2.2 Assault with minor injury 0.6 0.8 1.4 0.7 0.6 0.6 0.5 Assault with no injury 0.8 1.0 1.6 1.0 0.9 1.0 0.9 Wounding 0.5 0.6 0.9 0.6 0.5 0.6 0.5 Robbery 0.2 0.2 0.3 0.4 0.3 0.3 0.3 All personal crime 4.1 4.7 6.9 4.7 4.1 4.2 3.7 All crimes reported to BCS 11.0 15.1 19.4 12.6 10.9 11.3 10.1 1 Until 2000 respondents were asked to recall their experience of crime in the previous calendar year. From 2001/02 onwards the British Crime Survey (BCS) became a continuous survey and the recall period was changed to the 12 months prior to interview. 2 Includes theft of, or from, a vehicle, as well as attempts. 3 Includes thefts and attempted thefts from domestic garages, outhouses and sheds, not directly linked to the dwelling, as well as thefts from both inside and outside a dwelling. Source: British Crime Survey, Home Office Social Trends 39: 2009 edition Chapter 9: Crime and justice 131 9 According to the 2006 OCJS, the most common type of personal crime among ten to 25-year-olds was assault, at 17 per cent, with 11 per cent of young people being victims of assault without injury and 9 per cent victims of assault with injury. Males aged ten to 25 had the highest victimisation rates for these crimes, at 14 per cent and 12 per cent respectively, around double the rates for females (8 per cent and 6 per cent respectively). While the definition of personal victimisation in the survey is broadly consistent with the BCS, the questions are adjusted to make them suitable for the younger respondents, and are asked in a different context, so it is not possible to draw direct comparisons between the OCJS and BCS measures of victimisation. The 2006/07 BCS showed that in England and Wales, 2 per cent of individual mobile phone owners had their mobile stolen in the last 12 months, the same proportion as in 2005/06. Mobile phone theft varied by age of the victim with children aged 12 to 15 and young adults aged 16 to 24 being the most likely to experience mobile phone theft in the last 12 months, around 5 per cent of each group of owners (Figure 9.5). Around 2 per cent of adults aged between 25 and 44 had their mobile stolen in the last 12 months. The 2006/07 BCS asked adults aged 16 and over who had personally experienced a theft (therefore excluding other household members and children) about the circumstances of the theft. Nearly one-quarter (24 per cent) reported that the theft had taken place while the victim was on public transport or in another public place, such as a shop or hospital. A further 22 per cent had their phone stolen from a bar, pub or club. The 2007/08 BCS asked victims of violent incidents (including wounding, assault with minor injury, assault with no injury and robbery) whether they believed the offender to have been under the influence of alcohol or drugs (except in incidents where the victim perceived the offender to be under school-leaving age or could not describe the offender). More than two-fifths (45 per cent) of victims of violent offences believed the offender to be under the influence of alcohol. Table 9.4 Young people who were victims of personal crime:1 by age and sex, 2006 England & Wales Percentages Males Females All aged 10–2510–15 16–25 All 10–15 16–25 All Any personal thefts 17 11 13 8 11 10 12 Robbery 2 3 2 1 1 1 2 Theft from the person 7 5 5 3 5 4 5 Other personal thefts 11 6 8 5 7 6 7 Any assault 28 18 22 15 11 12 17 Assault (no injury) 21 10 14 11 7 8 11 Assault (with injury) 14 11 12 7 5 6 9 Any personal crime 38 27 31 22 20 21 26 1 In the 12 months prior to interview. Source: Offending, Crime and Justice Survey, Home Office Figure 9.5 Mobile phone owners experiencing theft:1 by age, 2006/07 England & Wales Percentages 1 Based on the number of people who experienced theft of at least one mobile phone in the last 12 months. Does not reflect the number of phones stolen. Source: British Crime Survey, Home Office 0 1 2 3 4 5 12–158–11 16–24 25–34 35–44 45–54 55–64 65–74 75 and over Chapter 9: Crime and justice Social Trends 39: 2009 edition 132 9 Violence committed by a stranger was the most common type of incident in which victims believed the offender was under the influence of alcohol (58 per cent) followed by violent incidents committed by an acquaintance (48 per cent) (Table 9.6). The most common type of offence was assault with minor injury, with around three-fifths (61 per cent) of victims seeing alcohol as a contributing factor. It is harder for victims to identify whether the perpetrator of their violent incident was under the influence of drugs but this too was most commonly identified in incidents of assault with minor injury (24 per cent). The introduction of The Licensing Act 2003 in November 2005 abolished set licensing hours in England and Wales with the aim of passing responsibility for licensing from the magistrates’ courts to local authorities. Although this led to some concerns about introducing a ’24-hour drinking culture’, the aim was to reduce the problems of heavy drinking and disorder associated with a standard closing time and, over the longer term, encourage a more relaxed drinking culture. The Home Office evaluation of the impact of the Act on crime and disorder found that there was little evidence to support concerns about increased violence. Comparing the 12 months before and after implementation, a survey of 30 police forces showed falls in the number of recorded incidents involving violence, criminal damage and harassment (1 per cent) and in serious violent crimes (5 per cent). However, the timing of these incidents changed with a small rise in the number of incidents between 6 pm and 6 am and a 25 per cent increase in the number of offences committed between 3 am and 6 am. In addition, the BCS Night Time Economy Module shows that there was no significant change following the introduction of the Act in the proportion of people who said they felt unsafe in town centres at night, or who had witnessed drunken anti-social behaviour in town centres. The 2007/08 BCS estimated that there were nearly 2.2 million violent incidents against adults in England and Wales, a decrease of 12 per cent since 2006/07 (see Table 9.3). Weapons were used in nearly one-quarter (24 per cent) of all violent incidents, the same proportion as in 2006/07. This proportion has remained stable over the last decade. Weapons were most commonly used in offences of robbery, wounding, and assault with no injury, with around one-quarter of these incidents each involving the use of some kind of weapon (23 per cent, 26 per cent and 27 per cent respectively). Hitting implements (including sticks and clubs) and knives were the most common weapons used in violent incidents reported in the 2007/08 BCS (used in 7 per cent and 6 per cent of incidents respectively). A knife was used in 15 per cent of robberies and 8 per cent of woundings. Nearly one-half (49 per cent) of victims of violent incidents in 2007/08 sustained a physical injury. In 2007/08 around one-fifth (19 per cent) of police-recorded serious offences in England and Wales, including attempted murder, wounding with intent to do grievous bodily harm (GBH), wounding or inflicting GBH (without intent) and robbery (of business or personal property) involved a knife or sharp instrument. In 2007/08 there were 17,343 crimes reported to the police in England and Wales in which a firearm was used, a 6 per cent decrease from 18,481 offences in 2006/07. The number of offences involving a firearm increased every year from 1998/99 (13,874 offences) to peak in 2002/03 and 2003/04 at around 24,000 offences. The number of firearm offences then began to decline and the decrease in 2007/08 was the fourth consecutive fall since 2003/04. Air weapons were reported to have been used in 7,478 offences in 2007/08, a decrease from 8,836 in 2006/07 (Figure 9.7), and accounted for more than two-fifths (43 per cent) of all firearm offences. However, offences involving a firearm excluding air weapons increased by 2 per cent between 2006/07 and 2007/08; from 9,645 to 9,865 offences. Handguns were the most common type of Table 9.6 Proportion of violent incidents where the offender was perceived to be under the influence of alcohol or drugs,1,2 2007/08 England & Wales Percentages Alcohol Drugs Yes No Yes No Type of violence Domestic 37 61 12 82 Mugging 17 63 13 58 Stranger 58 28 14 47 Acquaintance 48 46 28 51 Type of offence Wounding 48 42 15 60 Robbery 19 63 14 58 Assault with minor injury 61 32 24 49 Assault with no injury 44 47 20 56 All violence 45 45 19 56 1 Percentages do not sum to 100 per cent as victims could answer ‘don’t know’. 2 Question not asked if offenders were perceived to be of school age. Source: British Crime Survey, Home Office Social Trends 39: 2009 edition Chapter 9: Crime and justice 133 9 non-air weapon used, and were involved in more than two-fifths (42 per cent) of all non-air weapon firearm offences in 2007/08. Firearms are defined as having been involved in an incident if they have been discharged (fired), used as a blunt instrument against a person, or used as a threat. In 2007/08 more than nine in ten (92 per cent) air weapons involved in incidents were fired compared with around three-quarters (73 per cent) of imitation firearms, around one-half (53 per cent) of rifles, unidentified and ‘other’ weapons, and more than one-third (37 per cent) of shotguns. Handguns were the least likely to be fired with only 10 per cent of handguns involved in incidents being fired. However, handguns that were fired were the most likely firearm to result in a fatal or serious injury (36 per cent) compared with 1 per cent as a result of discharged air weapons. In Scotland in 2007/08 there were 1,125 firearm offences recorded by the police. More than one-half (576) involved air weapons (including air guns, air pistols, air rifles and BB guns). The proportion of crimes involving a firearm has decreased by 11 per cent since 2006/07 and those involving air weapons has decreased by 17 per cent. In Northern Ireland there were 544 crimes reported to the police in 2007/08 in which a firearm was used, a 9 per cent decrease compared with 2006/07. Between 2005/06 and 2006/07 there was a 35 per cent decrease. While crimes involving firearms excluding air weapons decreased by 12 per cent, those involving air weapons decreased by 2 per cent between 2006/07 and 2007/08. The risk of being a victim of homicide (which includes the offences of murder, manslaughter and infanticide) continues to be low in England and Wales. In 2007/08 there were 763 offences recorded, a 3 per cent increase on the number recorded in 2006/07 and a rate of 14.1 per million population. Homicide figures are based on the year they are recorded by the police and not the year they occur so trend data should be treated with caution (see Appendix, Part 9: Homicides). However, over the last ten years the homicide rate has remained relatively stable, between 13 and 15 per million population, apart from an increase in 2002/03 to 18 per million population. This increase resulted from 172 homicides attributed to Harold Shipman which, although took place over a number of years, were recorded in 2002/03 following Dame Janet Smith’s inquiry. Males are more at risk of homicide than females; around three-quarters (73 per cent) of all homicide victims were male in 2007/08. The risk was highest for men aged 16 to 20, at 45 per million population (Figure 9.8). This is a change from 2006/07 where men aged 21 to 29 had the highest risk of homicide, at 42 per million population compared with 29 per million for those aged 16 to 20. For females the highest risk of homicide in 2007/08 was for infants under one year old, at 30 per million population. The homicide rate for males was higher than that for females at all ages apart from those aged 70 and over when the rate was slightly lower. Figure 9.7 Crimes1 reported to the police in which a firearm had been used England & Wales Thousands 1 Changes in counting offences were made in April 1998 and the National Crime Recording Standard was implemented in April 2002. See Appendix, Part 9: National Crime Recording Standard. Source: Home Office 0 5 10 15 20 25 All weapons All weapons excluding air weapons Air weapons 1998/99 2001/02 2004/05 2007/08 Figure 9.8 Offences recorded as homicide:1 by sex and age of victim, 2007/08 England & Wales Rates per million population 1 Offences currently recorded as homicide as at 4 November 2008. Figures are subject to revision as cases are dealt with by the police or courts, or as further information comes to light. See Appendix, Part 9: Homicides. Source: Home Office 0 10 20 30 40 50 50–6930–4921–2916–2011–155–101–4Under 1 70 and over Males Females Chapter 9: Crime and justice Social Trends 39: 2009 edition 134 9 In 2007/08 more than one-third (35 per cent) of all homicide victims were apparently killed by sharp instruments. This was the most common method of killing for both male and female victims with 212 and 58 offences respectively. For males the second most common method was ‘hitting and kicking, etc.’ (140 offences) but for females it was strangulation, including asphyxiation (41 offences). In Scotland there were 114 offences currently recorded as homicide in 2007/08, a rate of 22 per million population. Around four-fifths (79 per cent) of the victims were male. People aged 16 to 30 were at the highest risk, with a rate of 38 homicides per million population overall, and men were again particularly at risk, at 64 per million population in this age group. However, as in England and Wales, the number of homicides in Scotland was very small and these offences accounted for 0.1 per cent of all violent crime (which includes homicide, attempted murder, sexual assault, abduction, serious assault, minor assault and robbery). In Northern Ireland there were 24 offences currently recorded as homicide in 2006/07, a rate of 14 per million population, the same as for England and Wales. Most of the victims (19) were men and the homicide rate was highest among men aged 30 to 49 years old with 11 of the male victims in this age group. Perceptions of crime The 2007/08 BCS reported that despite a decrease in the incidence of crime in England and Wales, almost two-thirds (65 per cent) of people perceived there to be more crime (either ‘a lot more’ or ‘a little more’) than two years ago in the country as a whole. This perception was unchanged since 2006/07 (Table 9.9). More than one-third (35 per cent) of respondents perceived that crime had increased a lot in the country as a whole. People were more positive about their local area, with 39 per cent perceiving there was either a little or a lot more crime than two years ago. The proportion of people perceiving more crime in the country as a whole has remained fairly stable since 2003/04, but the proportion perceiving more crime in their local area has decreased from 54 per cent in 2002/03. The Northern Ireland Crime Survey (NICS) showed that the proportions of people in Northern Ireland perceiving more crime in the country as a whole and in their local area were similar to those for England and Wales in 2007/08. However, both these proportions had decreased compared with 2006/07, from 73 per cent to 65 per cent for the whole country and from 44 per cent to 39 per cent for crime in the local area. Respondents to these crime surveys were asked how likely they thought they were to be victims of particular crimes in the 12 months following their interview. According to the 2007/08 BCS, 14 per cent of people in England and Wales thought they were likely (either ‘very likely’ or ‘fairly likely’) to be victims of burglary or violent crime and 23 per cent of car owners thought they were likely to be victims of vehicle crime. However, in the same year the actual incidence of these crimes reported to the BCS was much lower. Around 6 per cent of households reported being a victim of vehicle related theft or damage in the previous 12 months, 2 per cent reported being victims of burglary, and 3 per cent of adults had experienced violent crime in the last 12 months. Apart from men aged 16 to 24, the crime both men and women thought they were most likely to experience was vehicle crime (Figure 9.10). Men aged 16 to 24, however, perceived they were more likely to be victims of violent crime. When analysed by marital status, respondents who were separated were the most likely to think they would be a victim of vehicle crime (31 per cent) within the next 12 months, while one-fifth (20 per cent) of single people thought they were likely to be a victim of violent crime. However, people who were widowed were the least likely of all marital status groups to think that they would be a victim of vehicle crime, burglary or violent crime within the next 12 months. In 2007/08 both men and women in Northern Ireland felt they were more likely to be victims of vehicle crime than any other crime within the next 12 months. This was true for all ages although the perception was most prevalent among men aged 55 to 64 (28 per cent) and among women aged 25 to 34 (25 per cent). One-fifth (21 per cent) of young men aged 16 to Table 9.9 Perceptions of changing crime levels1 England & Wales Percentages Whole country Local area2 2001/02 65 51 2002/03 72 54 2003/04 65 48 2004/05 61 42 2005/06 63 42 2006/07 65 41 2007/08 65 39 1 British Crime Survey (BCS) respondents were asked if they thought there was more or less crime than two years ago and given the following options; ‘A lot more’, ‘a little more’, ‘about the same’, ‘a little less’ or ‘a lot less’. Data are the proportion of people who answered ‘a lot more’ or ‘a little more’. 2 Question only asked of respondents who had lived in their area for three years or more. Source: British Crime Survey, Home Office Social Trends 39: 2009 edition Chapter 9: Crime and justice 135 9 24 felt they were likely to be victims of violent crime within the next 12 months. Offenders In 2007, 1.41 million offenders were sentenced for indictable and summary offences in England and Wales (see Appendix, Part 9: Types of offence in England and Wales), compared with 1.42 million in 2006. Most of the offenders were male and of these 7 per cent were aged under 18. In 2007 the peak age for men being found guilty of, or cautioned for, one or more indictable offence was 17, with 6 per cent of men of this age being found guilty or cautioned, compared with 1 per cent of women of the same age (Figure 9.11). For females the peak age for being found guilty of, or cautioned for, an indictable offence was 15 (2 per cent). As young men and women entered their 20s the proportion of offenders started to decline but this happened at a younger age for women than for men. Less than 1 per cent of women at each age over the age of 20 were found guilty of, or cautioned for, an indictable offence in 2007 but for men the proportions did not decline to less than 1 per cent until the age of 45. In Northern Ireland 7,600 offenders were found guilty of, or cautioned for, indictable offences in 2006. Of these, 88 per cent were male. Young men aged 19 and 20 were the most likely to be offenders with nearly 4 per cent of all men in this age group being found guilty of, or cautioned for, an indictable offence. The proportion of women who were offenders was less than one-half of 1 per cent for all age groups. Theft and handling stolen goods accounted for 179,000 offences in England and Wales in 2007 and was the most common indictable offence for both men and women to be Figure 9.10 Perceived likelihood of being a victim of crime:1,2 by sex and age, 2007/08 England & Wales Percentages 1 Those who answered they were ‘fairly’ or ‘very likely’ to be victims of each crime within the next 12 months. See Appendix, Part 9: Perceived likelihood of being a victim of crime. 2 All respondents were asked, irrespective of whether or not they had been a victim of crime in the previous 12 months. Source: British Crime Survey, Home Office 0 5 10 15 20 25 30 0 5 10 15 20 25 30 16–24 25–34 35–44 45–54 55–64 65–74 75 and over 16–24 25–34 35–44 45–54 55–64 65–74 75 and over Vehicle crime Burglary Violent crime Vehicle crime Burglary Violent crime Men Women Figure 9.11 Offenders1 as a proportion of the population: by sex and age,2 2007 England & Wales Percentages 1 People found guilty of, or cautioned for, indictable offences in 2007. 2 Age 25 includes those offenders for whom age is not known. Source: Office for Criminal Justice Reform, Ministry of Justice 0 2 4 6 8 Males Females 10 20 30 40 50 60 70 and over Chapter 9: Crime and justice Social Trends 39: 2009 edition 136 9 found guilty of, or cautioned for; 30 per cent of male offences and 51 per cent of female offences (Figure 9.12). The next most common offences for men were drugs offences and violence against the person, with 78,000 and 77,000 offences respectively, 19 per cent each. The proportion of men found guilty of, or cautioned for, drugs offences in 2007 was double that of women (9 per cent). For women, the next most common offences, with 17,000 each, were violence against the person and other offences (17 per cent each). In Northern Ireland, the most common indictable offence for men to be found guilty of, or cautioned for in 2006, was violence against the person, accounting for 2,000 offences (30 per cent), followed by theft and handling stolen goods (20 per cent). For women, the most common offence to be found guilty of, or cautioned for (370 offences) was theft and handling stolen goods, accounting for two-fifths (40 per cent) of all offences. Of the 518,000 offenders found guilty of, or cautioned for, indictable offences in England and Wales in 2007, three-fifths (60 per cent) were sentenced. The type of sentence given depends on the offence committed and other factors that may be applied on a case-by-case basis (see Appendix, Part 9: Sentences and orders). The most common sentence for indictable offences in 2007 was a community sentence (34 per cent), with around one-half (46 per cent) of offenders sentenced for criminal damage and 43 per cent of those sentenced for burglary receiving this sentence (Table 9.13). Offenders committing indictable drugs offences were most commonly fined along with those convicted of ‘other indictable offences’ (32 per cent and 31 per cent respectively). More than one-half of those found guilty of sexual offences (56 per cent) and robbery (54 per cent) were sentenced to immediate custody. Motoring offences vary in severity and this is reflected in the variety of sentences given (see also Figure 9.17). Of those found guilty of indictable motoring offences in 2007, 29 per cent were sentenced to immediate custody, 26 per cent were given a community sentence and 23 per cent were fined. In Northern Ireland 7,600 offenders were sentenced for indictable offences in 2007. A fine was the most common sentence for all offences apart from robbery, sexual offences and burglary, where the most common sentence was immediate custody (85 per cent, 55 per cent and 45 per cent respectively). One aim of the criminal justice system is to try to prevent offenders from committing further crimes, so the measurement of reoffending is of considerable policy interest. One measure of adult reoffending, on which the Ministry of Justice reoffending target is based, is the frequency of reoffences committed per 100 offenders. This measure is based on the number of offences committed within one year by offenders who were released from prison or had commenced a court order under probation supervision. In 2006 there were 146 offences per 100 offenders, a decrease of 32 per cent since 2002 when the rate was 215 offences per 100 offenders. Another way to measure adult reoffending is the actual yes/no (binary) reoffending rate. This rate counts the proportion of adult offenders released from custody or commencing a court order under probation supervision who offended at least once during a one-year follow-up period, and where the offence resulted in a conviction at court (see Appendix, Part 9: Reoffenders). This measure is therefore based purely on the number of reoffenders, however many offences they may commit during the follow-up period. Of the offenders leaving prison or starting a community sentence in the first quarter of 2006, 39 per cent reoffended within one year, the lowest reoffending rate since the series began with the 2000 cohort and a decrease from the 42 per cent who reoffended in 2005. There was an overall decline in the reoffending rate by age; 48 per cent of 18 to 20-year-olds in 2006 reoffended within one year, more than double the rate among offenders aged 50 and over (Figure 9.14). However, offenders in this older age Figure 9.12 Offenders found guilty of, or cautioned for, indictable offences:1 by sex and type of offence, 2007 England & Wales Thousands 1 See Appendix, Part 9: Types of offence in England and Wales. 2 Includes fraud and forgery and indictable motoring offences. Source: Office for Criminal Justice Reform, Ministry of Justice 0 20 40 60 80 100 120 140 Males Females Theft and handling stolen goods Drug offences Violence against the person Burglary Criminal damage Robbery Sexual offences Other offences2 Social Trends 39: 2009 edition Chapter 9: Crime and justice 137 9 group had the greatest increase in the reoffending rate, increasing from 13 per cent in 2000 to 19 per cent in 2006. Reoffending among juveniles is measured in a similar way to adults and covers juveniles aged ten to 17 released from custody, starting a non-custodial court disposal or those given an out-of-court disposal (see Appendix, Part 9: Reoffenders – juveniles). In 2006 the reoffending rate for juveniles was the same as that for adults (39 per cent). Although this was slightly lower than the 40 per cent reoffending rate in 2000, the rate for juveniles has remained between 38 and 39 per cent since 2002. Juveniles committed 123 offences per 100 juvenile offenders in 2006, a 19 per cent decrease from the reoffending rate of 151 per 100 offenders in 2000. Prisons and sentencing Prison is the usual destination for offenders given custodial sentences or those who break the terms of their non-custodial sentence. The prison population (those held in prison or police cells, see Appendix, Part 9: Prison population for more details) in Great Britain was relatively stable in the 1980s and early 1990s but in the mid-1990s the population began to increase (Figure 9.15 overleaf). The largest increase, 10 per cent, occurred between 1996 and 1997. Apart from small decreases of less than 1 per cent in 1999 and 2000, the prison population increased every year since 1991 and in 2008 reached 91,000, almost double the population of 1980 and 4 per cent higher than in 2007. This 4 per cent increase in the average prison population in 2008 was recorded for both sentenced and remand (which includes untried and convicted but unsentenced) prisoners. Table 9.13 Offenders sentenced for indictable offences: by type of offence1 and type of sentence,2 2007 England & Wales Percentages Discharge Fine Community sentence Suspended sentence order Immediate custody Other All sentenced (=100%) (thousands) Theft and handling stolen goods 21 13 38 6 19 3 105.5 Drug offences 18 32 23 6 18 2 44.5 Violence against the person 7 5 38 17 30 4 42.1 Burglary 4 2 43 10 39 2 23.5 Fraud and forgery 17 11 32 12 26 2 19.9 Criminal damage 22 10 46 4 11 9 12.3 Motoring 4 23 26 16 29 2 5.5 Robbery - - 39 5 54 1 8.9 Sexual offences 3 3 27 9 56 3 5.1 Other offences 9 31 23 8 20 9 45.0 All indictable offences 14 16 34 9 24 4 312.3 1 See Appendix, Part 9: Types of offence in England and Wales. 2 See Appendix, Part 9: Sentences and orders. Source: Ministry of Justice 1 Percentage of all offenders reoffending at least once during the one-year follow-up period, where the reoffence resulted in conviction at court. Includes offenders aged 18 and over discharged from prison, or starting a court order supervised by the probation service, in the first quarter (January–March) of the year. Source: Ministry of Justice Figure 9.14 One-year reoffending rate:1 by age England & Wales Percentages 0 20 40 60 18–20 21–24 25–29 30–34 40–4935–39 50 and over 2000 2006 Chapter 9: Crime and justice Social Trends 39: 2009 edition 138 9 The annual average number of sentenced prisoners in Great Britain increased by 83 per cent between 1980 and 2008, from around 40,000 to 74,000, while the number of remand prisoners more than doubled, from 7,000 to 15,000. Northern Ireland’s prison population fell during the 1980s and 1990s to a low of 910 in 2001. One reason for the decrease in the late 1990s was the implementation of the Northern Ireland (Sentences) Act 1998, arising from the Belfast Agreement (Good Friday Agreement), which resulted in the release of a number of prisoners between 1998 and 2000. However, the prison population in Northern Ireland has increased progressively since that time and the population in 2007, of 1,470 prisoners, was around 61 per cent higher than in 2001. In 2007 the prison population rate in England and Wales was 149 prisoners per 100,000 population. This was 21 per cent higher than the EU-27 average rate of 123 per 100,000 population, and the seventh highest in the EU-27 (Figure. 9.16). The prison population rate in Scotland was 142 per 100,000 population (15 per cent higher than the EU average) but the population in Northern Ireland, at 83 per 100,000 population, was 32 per cent lower and the seventh lowest in the EU-27. With the exception of Luxembourg, England and Wales had the highest prison population rate of the original EU-15 member states (see Appendix, Part 4: Accession to the European Union (EU)). The highest rate of the EU-27 was in Estonia, at 322 per 100,000 population and the lowest was Denmark, at 62 per 100,000 population. However, comparing prison populations across the EU is difficult because the number of prisoners in custody at any one time depends on the individual penal systems in operation in each country. Prison is just one way of dealing with offenders and in recent years there has been an increase in the use of non-criminal proceedings, such as the use of fixed penalties (fines) for a number of different crimes, including motoring offences. Overall in 2006 there were a total of 12.7 million motoring offences in England and Wales, equivalent to a rate of 422 motoring offences per 1,000 licensed vehicles. The total number of offences dealt with increased from 9.5 million in 1996 to 13.7 million in 2004 although the number then decreased in each of the following two years to 2006. Although the number of motoring offences in 2006 was the lowest number dealt with since 2002, the number receiving penalty charge notices was at the highest level in the last decade; from 3.5 million in 1996 to 7.8 million in 2006 (Figure 9.17). This increase reflects the change in the treatment of summary motor offences, such as parking, from using criminal penalties 1 Includes prisoners held in police cells. 2 Includes non-criminal prisoners (for example, those held under the Immigration Act 1971). Source: Ministry of Justice; Scottish Government Figure 9.15 Average prison1 population Great Britain Thousands 0 20 40 60 80 100 1980 1985 1990 1995 2000 2005 2008 Total2 Remand Sentenced 1 As at 1 September. Number of prisoners, including pre-trial detainees/remand prisoners. 2 Data for England and Wales, Scotland and Northern Ireland are presented separately because of the different criminal justice systems in these countries. Source: Ministry of Justice Figure 9.16 Prison population:1 EU comparison,2 2007 Rates per 100,000 population 0 50 100 150 200 250 300 350 Estonia Latvia Lithuania Poland Czech Republic Luxembourg England and Wales Slovakia Spain Bulgaria Hungary Scotland Romania Netherlands Portugal Austria Greece France Malta Belgium Germany Cyprus Northern Ireland Italy Ireland Sweden Slovenia Finland Denmark EU-27 average Social Trends 39: 2009 edition Chapter 9: Crime and justice 139 9 pursued through the courts to a civil system in which offences are dealt with by the use of fines. This change was reflected in a decrease in the number of offences dealt with using court proceedings, to reach 1.7 million in 2006 and a further fall to 1.4 million in 2007 the lowest number dealt with in this way since the time series began in 1996. In 2007, court proceedings were most often taken for offences within the ‘licence, insurance and record-keeping offences’ category (including offences of ‘driving while disqualified’ and ‘using motor vehicle uninsured against third party risks’) amounting to 724,000, or 51 per cent of offences in 2007, compared with 921,000 in 2006. Driving while using a hand-held mobile phone became an offence on 1 December 2003 and in 2006 there were 168,500 offences of ‘use of hand-held mobile phone while driving’ dealt with by the police and parking attendants. Of these, around 98 per cent were dealt with by fixed penalties with the remainder being dealt with by court proceedings or written warnings. In 2007 there were 14,000 court proceedings for ‘use of hand-held mobile phone while driving’, up from 2,700 in 2006, reflecting the large number of police force areas taking action against drivers using hand-held mobile phones while driving. As well as dealing with offenders by the use of non-criminal proceedings such as fines, there are a number of measures aimed at reducing and preventing crime and reoffending. In England and Wales these measures include community orders, intended to move low-level offenders away from custodial sentences, which can be used instead of, or alongside, other sentences or orders. In addition there are a number of interventions aimed specifically at anti-social behaviour and, in particular, a range of measures to help parents and agencies such as youth offending teams to deal with anti-social behaviour by young people. The interventions available range from one-off fines (fixed penalty notices and penalty notices for disorder) to non-legal agreements, contracts and warnings (including acceptable behaviour contracts and parenting contracts) to court orders that prohibit the perpetrator from specific anti-social behaviours – anti-social behaviour orders (ASBOs) and parenting orders. ASBOs were introduced in 1999 and are aimed at protecting the public rather than punishing the perpetrator (see Appendix, Part 9: Anti-social behaviour orders (ASBOs)). However, while an ASBO is a civil order that will not appear on an individual’s criminal record, a breach of an ASBO is a criminal offence punishable by a fine or a custodial sentence. In 2006, 2,706 ASBOs were issued in England and Wales. Of these around three-fifths (1,625) were issued to individuals aged 18 and over, and two-fifths (1,054) were issued to ten to 17-year-olds (Figure 9.18). The number of ASBOs issued increased every year between 2001 and 2005, but between 2005 and 2006 there was a 34 per cent decrease. This decrease does not necessarily indicate a reduction in the offending behaviour but rather a change in the types of intervention used. Figure 9.17 Motor vehicle offences: by action taken England & Wales Millions 1 Civil notices issued by a council for apparent contraventions to the council’s Traffic Regulation Order (bylaw regulations). 2 Notices issued by police officers and police traffic wardens to motorists who commit parking and bus-lane offences governed by criminal law. 3 Includes written warnings and vehicle defect rectification scheme (VDRS) notices. Source: Ministry of Justice 0 2 4 6 8 Penalty charge notice1 Fixed penalty notice2 Court proceedings Other3 1996 1998 2000 2002 2004 2006 1 Issued at all HM Courts and reported to the Home Office by the Courts Service. Source: Home Office Figure 9.18 Number of anti-social behaviour orders (ASBOs) issued:1 by age England & Wales Numbers 0 500 1,000 1,500 2,000 2,500 3,000 200620052004200320022001 10–17 18 and over Chapter 9: Crime and justice Social Trends 39: 2009 edition 140 9 As well as ASBOs, acceptable behaviour contracts (ABCs) are written agreements that form a contract between the offender and their local authority, Youth Inclusion Support Panel, landlord or the police. The aim is to engage the individual in recognising the negative effects of their offending behaviour on others and encourage them to stop. Between October 2003 and September 2007 around 30,000 ABCs were issued in England and Wales. The Anti-Social Behaviour Act 2003 and the Criminal Justice Act 2003 introduced measures aimed at involving parents in reducing anti-social and offending behaviour in the form of parenting contracts (PCs) and parenting orders (POs). A PC is a voluntary written agreement between a youth offending team worker and the parents of a child who is, or is likely to become, involved in criminal or anti-social behaviour. A PO is made in similar circumstances by a court (criminal, family or magistrates’) and can be applied where parents are unwilling to co-operate (see Appendix, Part 9: Parenting contracts and parenting orders). Between October 2003 and September 2007 around 9,000 PCs and more than 2,000 POs were issued in England and Wales. As with ABCs, a large proportion (around two-fifths) of the total number of PCs and POs were issued between January and September 2007, indicating a rise in the use of these interventions as a form of reducing anti-social behaviour. Alongside this increase in the range of sentences and orders available for dealing with young offenders (aged ten to 17), a number of measures were also taken to reduce the time taken for them to be dealt with in the criminal justice system. In 1997 the Government set a target to maintain the average time from arrest to sentence specifically for persistent young offenders at or below 71 days (see Appendix, Part 9: Persistent young offenders). This was one-half the average number of days from arrest to sentence in 1996 of 142 days. The target of 71 days was reached in 2002 and has since remained below this level apart from in 2006, when it was 72 days (Figure 9.19). Between 2006 and 2007 there was a reduction of seven days in the time between arrest and sentencing to 65 days. The first half of 2008 showed a provisional decrease of a further seven days to 58 days. Overall performance against this target is largely determined by timeliness in the magistrates’ courts, where at least nine-tenths of all persistent young offender cases are heard. Although the average number of days between arrest and sentence is much longer for cases at Crown courts, and there was an increase in this time between 2005 and 2006 (from 191 to 214 days), this has little impact on overall timeliness because of the small number of cases involved. Police and other resources There were around 142,000 full-time equivalent police officers in England and Wales in 2008. Around one-quarter (24 per cent) were female and of these 85 per cent were constables, 10 per cent were sergeants and 3 per cent were inspectors. Less than 1 per cent of female police officers were in the senior Association of Chief Police Officers (ACPO) ranks. Overall there has been an increase in the number of police officers in the last ten years, from around 125,000 in 1998, and the proportion of female officers has increased from 16 per cent. The proportion of police officers who are from an ethnic minority group in England and Wales has also increased over the last decade, from 2 per cent in 1999 to 4 per cent in 2008 (Figure 9.20). In 2008, 4 per cent of constables were from an ethnic minority compared with 2 per cent of chief superintendents. For all other ranks of police officer around 3 per cent were from an ethnic minority. The proportion of officers who were from an ethnic minority group varied by police force area in England and Wales. In 2008 the London Metropolitan police force area had the highest proportion of ethnic minority officers, at 8 per cent. West Midlands police force had the second highest proportion, at 7 per cent, followed by Leicestershire with 6 per cent. The Figure 9.19 Average number of days from arrest to sentence for persistent young offenders1 England & Wales Days 1 Young offenders are those aged 10 to 17. See Appendix, Part 9: Persistent young offenders. 2 Target for average number of days between arrest and sentence, set by the Government in 1997, is 71 days. 3 Figures will differ from those previously published due to re-calculation of time series. See Appendix, Part 9: Average time from arrest to sentence. 4 Data are for January to June 2008. Source: Ministry of Justice 0 25 50 75 100 125 150 Number of days Target number of days2 1997 1999 2001 20033 2005 2007 20084 Social Trends 39: 2009 edition Chapter 9: Crime and justice 141 9 police force area with the lowest proportion of ethnic minority officers was North Wales, at less than one-half of 1 per cent. Of the 142,000 police officers in England and Wales in 2008, 2 per cent were Asian or Asian British and 1 per cent each were Black or Black British, or Mixed. In Northern Ireland the proportion of police officers who are from an ethnic minority group has increased every year since 2004, from 0.24 per cent to 0.4 per cent in 2008. According to the 2007/08 British Crime Survey, almost two-thirds (65 per cent) of people in England and Wales had overall confidence in the police in their local area (Table 9.21), a 1 percentage point increase since 2006/07. More than four-fifths (83 per cent) agreed that the local police would treat them with respect if they had contact with them and almost two-thirds (64 per cent) agreed that their local police would treat everyone fairly regardless of who they are, and that they understand the issues affecting their community (62 per cent). People had the least confidence in relying on their local police to deal with minor crimes (43 per cent). In Northern Ireland three-fifths (60 per cent) of people had overall confidence in the local police in 2007/08. Four-fifths (81 per cent) agreed that the police would treat them with respect if they had contact with them, around the same proportion as those in England and Wales. The proportions of people agreeing that the police treat everyone fairly regardless of who they are and that they can be relied on to deal with minor crimes were the same as those for England and Wales (64 per cent and 43 per cent respectively). The 2007/08 BCS showed that the level of confidence that people in England and Wales had in the criminal justice system (CJS) as a whole had increased compared with 2006/07 in five of the seven areas covered. In particular, the proportion of people who were fairly or very confident that the CJS was effective in bringing people who commit crimes to justice increased by 3 percentage points since 2006/07 to 44 per cent. This is the same increase as the proportion who were either very or fairly confident that the CJS meets the needs of victims of crime (from 33 per cent to 36 per cent between 2006/07 and 2007/08). These increases follow a general decrease in confidence between 2005/06 and 2006/07. The CJS is one of the major public services in England and Wales. It comprises the Police Service, the Crown Prosecution Service, HM Courts Service, the National Offender Management Service (covering prisons and probation) and the Youth Justice Board. HM Courts Service is responsible for managing the magistrates’ courts, the Crown courts, county courts, the High Court and Court of Appeal in England and Wales (see Appendix, Part 9: Courts system in England and Wales). The judiciary, that is the judges, magistrates and other adjudicators as well as support personnel who keep the courts system running smoothly, account for a large proportion of the courts system resources. In 2008 there were more than 3,800 members of the judiciary serving in England and Wales, of which the largest group (34 per cent) were recorders Figure 9.20 Ethnic1 minority officers as a proportion of all police officers2,3 England & Wales Percentages 1 See Appendix, Part 1: Classification of ethnic groups. 2 As at 31 March in each year. 3 Proportions for 1999 to 2002 were calculated using the headcount ethnic minority officer strength as a proportion of all full-time equivalent officer strength. The proportions from 2003 were calculated using full-time equivalent ethnic minority strength as a proportion of all full-time equivalent officer strength. Source: Home Office 0 1 2 3 4 5 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 2008 Table 9.21 Perceptions1 of the local police, 2007/08 England & Wales Percentages Would treat you with respect if you had contact with them 83 Treat everyone fairly regardless of who they are 64 Understand the issues that affect this community 62 Are dealing with things that matter to people in the community 51 Can be relied upon to be there when you need them 48 Can be relied on to deal with minor crimes 43 Overall confidence in the local police2 65 1 Proportion of respondents who strongly agreed/tended to agree with the statement. 2 Based on question ‘Taking everything into account I have confidence in the police in this area’. Source: British Crime Survey, Home Office Chapter 9: Crime and justice Social Trends 39: 2009 edition 142 9 (barristers or solicitors who are appointed part-time judges). A further one-quarter (25 per cent) of the judiciary were deputy district judges, 17 per cent were circuit judges and 15 per cent were district judges. Four-fifths (81 per cent) of the total judiciary were men (Table 9.22). Of the women in the judiciary, 35 per cent were deputy district judges and 27 per cent were recorders. The most common position to be held by men was recorder (36 per cent) (see Appendix, Part 9: Judiciary of England and Wales for further information on the separate roles in the judicial system). In 2008, 4 per cent of the judiciary in England and Wales were from an ethnic minority group; 7 per cent of deputy district judges (magistrates’ courts), 5 per cent of recorders and district judges (county courts), and smaller proportions, or none, among more senior positions. Table 9.22 Composition of the judiciary:1 by sex and ethnic group,2 20083 England & Wales Percentages Sex Ethnicity All (numbers)Male Female White Ethnic minority group Heads of Division 100.0 0.0 100.0 0.0 5 Lords of Appeal in Ordinary 91.7 8.3 100.0 0.0 12 Lord Justices of Appeal 91.9 8.1 100.0 0.0 37 High Court judges 90.0 10.0 97.3 2.7 110 Circuit judges 86.7 13.3 96.9 3.1 653 Recorders 85.1 14.9 95.3 4.7 1,305 Judge advocates 100.0 0.0 100.0 0.0 9 Deputy judge advocates 91.7 8.3 100.0 0.0 12 District judges (county courts) 77.6 22.4 95.4 4.6 438 District judges (magistrates’ courts) 77.2 22.8 97.8 2.2 136 Deputy district judges (county courts) 72.7 27.3 96.0 4.0 773 Deputy district judges (magistrates’ courts) 76.0 24.0 92.8 7.2 167 Masters, registrars, costs judges and district judges (Principal Registry of the Family Division) 77.1 22.9 97.9 2.1 48 Deputy masters, deputy registrars, deputy costs judges and deputy district judges (Principal Registry of the Family Division) 66.1 33.9 95.7 4.3 115 All 81.0 19.0 95.9 4.1 3,820 1 See Appendix, Part 9: Judiciary of England and Wales. 2 See Appendix, Part 1: Classification of ethnic groups. 3 As at 1 April 2008. Source: Judicial Database, Judiciary of England and Wales Crime and justice Crime levels Offences and victims Perceptions of crime Offenders Prisons and sentencing Police and other resources work_ipvvt6y33natbhz5su53isvt3q ---- Microsoft Word - The Extradition of Julian Assange Final Chair Report-2.docx 1 Forum: International Court of Justice Issue: The Extradition of Julian Assange (United Kingdom V. Ecuador) Student Officer: Anas Soliman (ICJ President), Zeina Gohar (ICJ Chair) I- Introduction Since June of 2012, Julian Assange’s extradition case has been notorious for being one of the most controversial legal and political disputes, given the nature of the numerous parties involved. Julian Assange is an Australian journalist and publisher, mostly renowned for being the founder and editor of WikiLeaks1, a non-profit organization that facilitates the anonymous leakage of information and the exposition of wrongdoing2. In 2010, during his trip to Sweden, it was reported that Julian Assange sexually assaulted two Swedish women1. After his return to the UK, Swedish prosecutors issued a European Arrest Warrant, which was certified by the Serious Organized Crime Agency, the SOCA, demanding Assange’s extradition and return to Sweden in order to proceed with the investigations1. Since the establishment of WikiLeaks, the organization has been releasing secret and classified documents belonging or pertaining to the United States government1, which have caused it great embarrassment. Subsequently, the US government initiated a criminal investigation, which targeted Assange with espionage charges1. Moreover, the US military has officially labeled Julian Assange as a wanted individual and an “enemy of the United States”3. The United States and Sweden share an extradition treaty, which means that Assange is under the threat of extradition to the United States if he is extradited to Sweden4. Escaping a threat of eventual extradition to the United States, Assange sought political asylum in the embassy of Ecuador in the UK, which he was granted finding that he “could at any moment find himself in a situation likely to endanger life, safety or personal integrity”1. Through its application to the ICJ, the United Kingdom seeks to confirm that Assange is not a political refugee and that his political asylum has no legal foundations, thus authorizing his extradition to Sweden. On the other hand, Ecuador aims to confirm that Assange’s Human rights are severely threatened, therefore justifying his blatant recognition as a political refugee, in order facilitate his safe passage out of the UK. II- Definition of Key Terms Refugee: A refugee is someone who "owing to a well-founded fear of being persecuted for reasons of race, religion, nationality, membership of a particular social group or political opinion, is outside the country of his nationality, and is unable to, or owing to such fear, is unwilling to avail himself of the protection of that country."5 European Arrest Warrant: The European arrest warrant is a judicial decision valid throughout all member states of the European Union “issued by a Member State with a view to the arrest and surrender by another Member State of a requested person, for the purposes of conducting a criminal prosecution or executing a custodial sentence or detention order.”6                                                                                                                 1 "Extraditing Assange." Justice For Assange. Justice4assange.com, Web. 8 July 2014 2 "About WikiLeaks." WikiLeaks. Wikileaks.org, 5 July 2011. Web. 12 July 2014 3 Dorling, Philip. "US Calls Assange 'enemy of State'" The Sydney Morning Herald. Web. 12 July 2014 4 Baker, Scott, David Perry, and Anand Doobay. "A Review Of The United Kingdom's Extradition Arrangements." n. pag. Gov.uk. 30 Sept. 2011. Web. 12 July 2014 5 "Refugees." UNHCR. Web. 09 July 2014   6 "Law No. 65/2003 of 23 August." Portuguese Legislation in English. GDDC, Web. 12 July 2014 2 WikiLeaks: WikiLeaks is a non-profit organization, which has a “goal to bring important news and information to the public”, and provides an “innovative, secure and anonymous way for sources to leak information to the organization’s journalists.”7 Extradition: “The surrender of an alleged criminal usually under the provisions of a treaty or statute by one authority (as a state) to another having jurisdiction to try the charge.”8 Journalist: “A person engaged in journalism, who is a writer or editor for a news medium and aims at a mass audience.”9 Political Asylum: The protection granted by a nation to someone who has left their native country as a political refugee. III- Background Information Julian Assange is an Australian journalist and activist that has aroused great concern among numerous governments since he initiated the WikiLeaks organization in 200710. WikiLeaks is an international, online, non profit organization dedicated to bringing “important news and information to the public”. The WikiLeaks organization has disclosed hundreds of classified information and published thousands of secret government documents in order to achieve its purpose of bringing truth and information to the public. The WikiLeaks website has published more than 1.2 million documents just within a year of its initiation11. Assange’s organization met hostile responses from governments all around the world. In 2009, the Australian Communications and Media Authority added WikiLeaks to the list of sites to be banned after the implementation of its mandatory Internet filtering scheme12. The United States government openly condemned the actions of WikiLeaks and the Obama administration along with the U.S. Army, Federal Bureau of Investigation and the U.S. Department of Justice have pursued personal legal actions towards Assange. The Obama administration is attempting to bring him to court on grounds that his organization “encourages the theft of government property”13. The US government has reportedly asked other parties such as the UK, Germany and Australia to limit his travel across international borders and consider bringing him to international court. WikiLeaks and its founder did however gain much support from other countries and even the United Nations. Following Assange’s arrest in the UK in 2010, Brazil’s President, Luiz Inacio Lula da Silva, expressed his solidarity with Assange and his organization, and went on to state that an attack on Assange or any volunteers or employees of his organization is an “attack on freedom of expression”14. Later that year, the government of Ecuador offered Assange residency in Ecuador so he may freely publish the information his organization possesses with no fear of arrest or surveillance, according to                                                                                                                 7 "About WikiLeaks." WikiLeaks. Wikileaks.org, 5 July 2011. Web. 12 July 2014 8 "Definition of Extradition." Merriam Webster. Web. 12 July 2014 9 "Definition of Journalist." Merriam Webster. Web. 12 July 2014 10 "About WikiLeaks." WikiLeaks. Wikileaks.org, 5 July 2011. Web. 12 July 2014 11 "WikiLeaks Introduction." WikiLeaks.org. Web. 12 July 2014 12 "Australia Secretly Censors Wikileaks Press Release." WikiLeaks.org. Web. 12 July 2014 13 Freeman, Colin. "Rape Claim against Wikileaks Founder Julian Assange Withdrawn." Telegraph.co.uk. 21 Aug. 2010. Web. 12 July 2014 14 "President Lula Shows Support for Wikileaks (English/Español/Italiano Subtitles)." YouTube. Web. 12 July 2014 3 Ecuador’s Deputy Foreign Minister, Kinto Lucas. However, President Rafael Correa later forfeited the offer to Assange and refuted Lucas’s statements15. The United Nations Special Rapporteur for Freedom of Opinion and Expression, Frank LaRue, agreed that Assange was a “martyr of free speech” and he later expressed that neither Assange nor his respective coworkers should be held accountable for any of the disclosed information, rather it is the sources that leaked the information that should be held accountable by the entities to which they pertain to16. In mid August 2010, Assange was charged by the Swedish authorities for the sexual assault of two Swedish women17. Swedish authorities issued a European Arrest Warrant, requesting that the journalist returns to Sweden immediately for questioning regarding the sexual assault allegations. This arrest warrant was later certified by the United Kingdom Serious Crime Agency. The following day, Assange peacefully surrendered to British police, pleading innocence. In February 2011, a hearing took place before the Chief Magistrate of England and Wales. The European Arrest Warrant was labeled as valid and after two unsuccessful appeals the Supreme Court of the United Kingdom released a statement in 2012 admitting the United Kingdom’s legal obligation to extradite Assange to Sweden for questioning18. On 19 June 2012, Assange sought diplomatic asylum in the Ecuadorian embassy in London, where he has remained since. UK government officials have stated that Assange will be arrested and immediately extradited to Sweden once he steps foot outside the doors of the embassy19. In late November 2010, WikiLeaks released a total of 251,000 diplomatic cables. Subsequently, the United States Department of Justice launched a full-scale criminal investigation on Assange20. The publication of the government documents unleashed great chaos and outrage in America. In December 2010 Michael Huckabee, the 44th Governor of Arkansas and formal presidential candidate, called for the assassination of Julian Assange21. The United States seeks to prosecute Assange in American court under the Espionage Act of 1917 for colluding with Chelsea Manning22, the US military official that illegally extracted the 251,000 documents that were published by WikiLeaks. If found guilty, Assange could face conviction or even a death penalty. However, the grounds on which the US wishes to prosecute Assange are still debated and they might not be enough for the court to find the accused guilty. Furthermore, the United States has not yet submitted an official extradition request, nor is it clear in the extradition treaty it has with Sweden. Whether Sweden would have the rights to extradite Assange to the US under the extradition treaty also remains unclear. In order to bring an end to the case of the internationally wanted Julian Assange, the United Kingdom has applied to the United Nation’s International Court of Justice to determine whether Ecuador’s diplomatic                                                                                                                 15 "Ecuador Offers Asylum to WikiLeaks Founder." The Jerusalem Post. 30 Nov. 2011. Web. 12 July 2014 16 Hall, Eleanor. "The World Today with Eleanor Hall." The World Today. Web. 12 July 2014 17 Davies, Nick. "10 Days in Sweden: The Full Allegations against Julian Assange." The Guardian. Guardian News and Media, 18 Dec. 2010. Web. 10 July 2014 18 Green, David A. "The Legal Mythology of the Extradition of Julian Assange."New Statesman. 3 Sept. 2012. Web. 12 July 2014 19 Davies, Lizzy, and Jo Adetunji. "Julian Assange Granted Asylum by Ecuador - as It Happened." Theguardian.com. Guardian News and Media, 16 Aug. 2012. Web. 12 July 2014 20 "Extraditing Assange." Justice For Assange. Justice4assange.com, Web. 8 July 2014 21 Collins, Nick. "WikiLeaks: Guilty Parties 'should Face Death Penalty'"Telegraph.co.uk. 1 Dec. 2012. Web. 12 July 2014 22 Kohn, Stephen M. "A Sad Day for the US If the Espionage Act Is Used against WikiLeaks." Theguardian.com. Guardian News and Media, 15 Dec. 2010. Web. 12 July 2014 4 asylum has proper legal foundations, in reference to the Convention and Protocol on the Status of Refugees, thus determining if Ecuador is under a legal obligation to surrender Assange to British custody in order to facilitate the UK’s obligation of extraditing him to Sweden. IV- Major Parties Involved The United Kingdom The United Kingdom Serious Crime Agency validated the European Arrest Warrant issued by Sweden and admitted its obligation to turn Assange over to Swedish authorities in December 2010. The following day, London police arrested the accused after he peacefully turned himself over to a local police station, pleading his innocence23. In February of 2011 the European Arrest Warrant was officially certified at a hearing before the Chief Magistrate of England and Wales. The judgment was unsuccessfully appealed twice. In June of 2012, the Supreme Court of the United Kingdom released a statement admitting the United Kingdom’s duty to hand Assange over to Swedish authorities. On the 19th of June 2012, Julian Assange sought asylum in the Embassy of Ecuador in London, where he has remained until today. London Metropolitan police forces surrounded the embassy and have also remained stationed there ever since. British authorities could state no clearer that police will arrest Assange once he steps foot outside the premises of the embassy. Shortly before the Ecuadorian embassy granted the wanted man safe asylum, British authorities threatened to invade the embassy’s premises to arrest Assange, violating the terms of the Vienna Conventions and dismissing the building’s diplomatic status. This threat was however withdrawn after it met great international condemnation and disapproval24. The Republic of Ecuador Ecuador, upholding its duty to protect individuals’ “freedom of expression” as explained by foreign minister Ricardo Patino25, continues to grant Julian Assange political asylum. Assange entered the Ecuadorian embassy, located on British territory, on the 19th of June 2012, seeking asylum, given his fears of persecution by the United States government and Swedish authorities.26 On the following August the 16th, Ecuador announced that Assange’s fears of persecution were well-founded, thus officially granting him political and diplomatic asylum.23 Ecuador cited that Assange’s indictment for crimes of a political nature is the basis of his request, and that Ecuador finds that he, as a result of his dedicated defense of freedom of expression and press, is facing a situation involving an imminent danger of political persecution, which could eventually violate his rights, integrity and could become a risk to his personal safety.27 The Constitution of the Republic of Ecuador clearly recognizes the right of asylum and its “extradition laws prevent the extradition of any person whose life or safety could suffer as a result of the extradition”27. Thus, Ecuador maintains that it is not in violation of the Extradition Treaty between the UK and itself, given that it regards Assange as a political refugee whom is no longer eligible for extradition. Ecuador continues its efforts to protect Assange’s rights by not allowing him to be extradited to Sweden “without adequate safeguards against US threat”24. As long as Sweden continues its refusal to provide such safeguards, Ecuador finds itself obligated to shelter Assange as a political victim and refugee, thus refusing to hand him in to the British authorities.                                                                                                                 23 "Wikileaks' Assange Refused Bail." BBC News. 8 Dec. 2012. Web. 12 July 2014 24 "Extraditing Assange." Justice For Assange. Justice4assange.com, Web. 8 July 2014 25 "Ecuador to Continue Assange Asylum." BBC News. 17 June 2013. Web. 12 July 2014 26 "Extraditing Assange." Justice For Assange. Justice4assange.com, Web. 8 July 2014 27 "Ecuador Grants Asylum to Julian Assange. (Press Conference)."WikiLeaks.org. 17 Aug. 2012. Web. 12 July 2014 5 Kingdom of Sweden In 2010, Swedish authorities came across evidence proving that the founder of WikiLeaks had sexually assaulted two Swedish citizens. An investigation was launched and authorities issued a European Arrest Warrant, demanding the accused’s immediate return to Sweden for questioning28. The investigation is forcibly put on hold, as Swedish authorities await Assange’s return until today. Sweden shares extradition treaties with both the United Kingdom and the United States of America. Under the terms of the treaty with the United Kingdom, it is clearly nonnegotiable that the UK is legally obligated to extradite Assange to Sweden, as under the terms of the European Arrest Warrant29. Sweden’s extradition treaty with the United States however is what sparks controversy. Under the terms of the treaty, the assertion that Sweden is under legal and international obligation to extradite Assange to the US is doubted30. This is due to many reasons that are clearly presented within the clauses of the treaty. United States of America Since the establishment of Julian Assange’s non-profit organization, WikiLeaks, secret and classified documents belonging or pertaining to the United States government have been released31, causing it great embarrassment. In 2010, Assange oversaw the largest publication of over half a million documents from the Pentagon and US State Department, which included precise details elucidating the deaths of thousands in Iraq and Afghanistan.31 Consequently, the US government initiated a criminal investigation, which targeted Assange and his associates with espionage charges31. The United States government openly condemned the actions of WikiLeaks, and the Obama administration along with the U.S. Army, FBI and the U.S. Department of Justice have pursued personal legal actions towards Assange. Moreover, the US military has officially labeled Julian Assange as a wanted individual and an “enemy of the United States”32. Even though the United States has not yet issued an extradition request, Assange fears his eventual extradition to the United States. Assange is in danger of facing charges including espionage under the Espionage Act, which could eventually result in a death penalty, if it is within jurisdiction. Also, the United States and Sweden share an extradition treaty, which means that Assange is under the threat of extradition to the United States if he is extradited to Sweden33. However, no official charges or extradition requests have been filed by the United States against Assange.                                                                                                                 28 Davies, Nick. "10 Days in Sweden: The Full Allegations against Julian Assange." The Guardian. Guardian News and Media, 18 Dec. 2010. Web. 10 July 2014 29 Green, David A. "The Legal Mythology of the Extradition of Julian Assange."New Statesman. 3 Sept. 2012. Web. 12 July 2014 30 "Extradition for Criminal Offences." Swedish Government. Web. 12 July 2014 31 "Extraditing Assange." Justice For Assange. Justice4assange.com, Web. 8 July 2014 32 Dorling, Philip. "US Calls Assange 'enemy of State'" The Sydney Morning Herald. Web. 12 July 2014 33 Baker, Scott, David Perry, and Anand Doobay. "A Review Of The United Kingdom's Extradition Arrangements." n. pag. Gov.uk. 30 Sept. 2011. Web. 12 July 2014 6 V- Important Events & Chronology Date (Day/Month/Year) Event 4 October 2006 Julian Assange launches WikiLeaks in Iceland. 20 August 2010 Following reports of rape and molestation, Swedish prosecutors order the arrest of Assange. 26 August 2010 The prosecutor pursuant to the Council of the European Union issues a European Arrest Warrant. 28 August 2010 WikiLeaks issues more than 250,000 US diplomatic cables, which is regarded as a “serious damage to national US security”. 6 October 2010 The UK Serious Organized Crime Agency certifies the European Arrest Warrant. 19 June 2012 Assange enters the Ecuador’s embassy in London. 20 June 2012 British police forces surround the Ecuadorian embassy, where they have remained since. 26 August 2012 Ecuadorian government officially grants Assange political and diplomatic asylum granted by the Ecuadorian Embassy VI- Related Documents Vienna Convention on Diplomatic Relations The Vienna Convention on Diplomatic Relations provides an overview of the structure for diplomatic relations between sovereign countries and it encompasses the certain freedoms of a diplomatic mission. This document preserves the concept of diplomatic immunity. 189 States are parties to this convention. Organization of American States (OAS) Convention of Diplomatic Asylum 1954 As the right to diplomatic asylum is not established in international law, the Organization of American States Convention on Diplomatic Asylum is regarded as the only treaty in the world that addresses the concept of diplomatic asylum. The convention was an attempt in 1954 by Latin American countries to recognize the right to diplomatic asylum as a principle of international law. Ecuador is one of 14 signatories of this treaty, and this treaty heavily influences its foreign and diplomatic affairs. The fact that neither the United Kingdom nor Sweden is bound to this treaty, questions either party’s legal obligation to respect or even recognize Ecuador’s grant of asylum to subjects such as Julian Assange. Convention and Protocol Relating to the Status of Refugees The Convention Relating to the Status of Refugees (CRSR) is a United Nations multilateral treaty that defines a refugee, the rights of a refugee that is granted asylum and the responsibilities of any nation that provides asylum. Bilateral Extradition Treaty of 1880 Between UK and Ecuador The extradition treaty the UK and Ecuador are dually bound to outlines the foundation of extradition between the two entities. The treaty respects the OAS Convention of Diplomatic Asylum and its terms that the United Kingdom is not bound to, which causes controversy between the two parties. It is also noteworthy that the treaty denotes that Ecuador is one of few nations that do not extradite their own nationals. Convention on Extradition Between The United States of America and Sweden 7 This document provides the terms of the Extradition Treaty between the United States and Sweden. It is a document that causes debate regarding the duty of Sweden to extradite Julian Assange to the United States, as it is argued that the terms of the convention exclude the case of Julian Assange. Council Framework Decision on the European Arrest Warrant and the Surrender Procedures Between Member States This Council Framework Decision of 13 June, 2002 provides an encompassing understanding of the European Arrest Warrant including the definition, scope, and obligation to execute the warrant. It also includes the grounds for optional and mandatory non-execution of the warrant as well as the procedures to be taken during the surrender of an extradited individual from one entity to another. This document specifies the basis on which the United Kingdom should extradite individuals to nations part of the European Union. VII- Useful Links 1. http://www.government.se/sb/d/2710/a/15435 2. https://www.gov.uk/extradition-processes-and-review 3. http://www.unog.ch/80256EDD006B8954/(httpAssets)/7F83006DA90AAE7FC1256F260034B806 /$file/Vienna%20Convention%20(1961)%20-%20E.pdf 4. http://www.oas.org/juridico/english/treaties/a-46.html 5. http://www.unhcr.org/3b66c2aa10.html 6. http://internationalextraditionblog.files.wordpress.com/2010/12/us-sweden-extradition-treaty- 14-ust-1845.pdf 7. https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/117680/european -arrest-warrant.pdf 8. http://justice4assange.com/extraditing-assange.html#UKVETO VIII- Bibliography "About WikiLeaks." WikiLeaks. Wikileaks.org, 5 July 2011. Web. 12 July 2014 "Australia Secretly Censors Wikileaks Press Release." WikiLeaks.org. Web. 12 July 2014 Baker, Scott, David Perry, and Anand Doobay. "A Review Of The United Kingdom's Extradition Arrangements." n. pag. Gov.uk. 30 Sept. 2011. Web. 12 July 2014 Collins, Nick. "WikiLeaks: Guilty Parties 'should Face Death Penalty'" Telegraph.co.uk. 1 Dec. 2012. Web. 12 July 2014 Davies, Lizzy, and Jo Adetunji. "Julian Assange Granted Asylum by Ecuador - as It Happened." Theguardian.com. Guardian News and Media, 16 Aug. 2012. Web. 12 July 2014 8 Davies, Nick. "10 Days in Sweden: The Full Allegations against Julian Assange." The Guardian. Guardian News and Media, 18 Dec. 2010. Web. 10 July 2014 "Definition of Extradition." Merriam Webster. Web. 12 July 2014 "Definition of Journalist." Merriam Webster. Web. 12 July 2014 Dorling, Philip. "US Calls Assange 'enemy of State'" The Sydney Morning Herald. Web. 12 July 2014 "Ecuador Grants Asylum to Julian Assange. (Press Conference)." WikiLeaks.org. 17 Aug. 2012. Web. 12 July 2014 "Ecuador Offers Asylum to WikiLeaks Founder." The Jerusalem Post. 30 Nov. 2011. Web. 12 July 2014 "Ecuador to Continue Assange Asylum." BBC News.17 June 2013. Web. 12 July 2014 "Extraditing Assange." Justice For Assange. Justice4assange.com, Web. 8 July 2014 "Extradition for Criminal Offences." Swedish Government. Web. 12 July 2014 Freeman, Colin. "Rape Claim against Wikileaks Founder Julian Assange Withdrawn." Telegraph.co.uk. 21 Aug. 2010. Web. 12 July 2014 Green, David A. "The Legal Mythology of the Extradition of Julian Assange." New Statesman. 3 Sept. 2012. Web. 12 July 2014 Hall, Eleanor. "The World Today with Eleanor Hall." The World Today. Web. 12 July 2014 Kohn, Stephen M. "A Sad Day for the US If the Espionage Act Is Used against WikiLeaks." Theguardian.com. Guardian News and Media, 15 Dec. 2010. Web. 12 July 2014 "Law No. 65/2003 of 23 August." Portuguese Legislation in English. GDDC, Web. 12 July 2014 "President Lula Shows Support for Wikileaks (English/Español/Italiano Subtitles)." YouTube. Web. 12 July 2014 "Refugees." UNHCR. Web. 09 July 2014 "Wikileaks' Assange Refused Bail." BBC News., 8 Dec. 2012. Web. 12 July 2014 "WikiLeaks Introduction." WikiLeaks.org. Web. 12 July 2014.   work_iqq5ckwupbegzpfgojzly2uo6m ---- Cultural Pluralism and Epistemic Injustice Göran Collste Linköping University Abstract For liberalism, values such as respect, reciprocity, and tolerance should frame cultural encounters in multicultural societies. However, it is easy to disregard that power differences and political domination also influence the cultural sphere and the relations between cultural groups. In this essay, I focus on some challenges for cultural pluralism. In relation to Indian political theorist Rajeev Bhargava, I discuss the meaning of cultural domination and epistemic injustice and their historical and moral implications. Bhargava argued that as a consequence of colonialism, “indigenous cultures” were inferiorized, marginalized, and anonymized. Although cultures are often changing due to external influences, I argue that epistemic injustice implies that a culture is forced to subjection, disrespected, and considered as inferior and that it threatens the dominated people’s epistemic framework, collective identity, and existential security. Finally, I refer to John Rawls’s theory of political liberalism as a constructive approach to avoid parochialism and Western cultural domination. Keywords cultural pluralism; epistemic injustice; liberalism; colonialism; historical justice; globalization; Rajeev Bhargava; John Rawls Introduction For liberalism, values such as respect, reciprocity, and tolerance should frame cultural encounters in multicultural societies. However, it is easy to disregard that power differences and political domination also influence the cultural sphere. In the age of colonialism, Europe controlled large parts of the world for more than 400 years. In this essay, I discuss cultural pluralism from this historical point of departure. In relation to Indian political theorist Rajeev Bhargava, I discuss the meaning of cultural domination and epistemic injustice and their historical and moral implications. Finally, I refer to John Rawls’s theory of political liberalism as a constructive approach to avoid parochialism and Western cultural domination. © 2019 Göran Collste, published by Sciendo. This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivs 4.0 License. Journal of Nationalism, Memory & Language Politics Volume 13 Issue 2  DOI 10.2478/jnmlp-2019-0008 * Göran Collste, Linköping University, Centre for Applied Ethics, 58183 Linköping, Sweden; Goran. collste@liu.se Unauthentifiziert | Heruntergeladen 01.10.19 07:33 UTC 2 Journal of Nationalism, Memory & Language Politics 13(2) Culture is a broad and vague concept. In this essay, culture and cultural differences relate to questions of epistemic frameworks, religions, traditions, and political principles. It could be questionable to use such a broad concept of culture, but it does not pose a problem for my argument. Epistemic Injustice For many years, I was responsible for an international master’s program in applied ethics. I taught a course on globalization and global justice, and one aspect was global rectificatory justice: how can we understand global justice from the perspective of historical justice? What are the implications of colonialism for today’s global relations? Is the legacy of colonialism still visible? I raised the question whether colonialism had left any morally relevant traces in the present, and a student from Pakistan spoke out and explained with some anger in her voice: “Yes, certainly! Everything Pakistani is today considered of less worth compared to the West: we consider our own history as shameful and we feel that we are still slaves under the British rulers. These feelings have also a cultural impact today; to be beautiful is to have blond hair, not black, to be civilized is to eat with knife and fork, not to eat in our traditional way, and our traditional languages are superseded by English.” The student from Pakistan felt that her culture is of less worth than the Western. This experience has its background in the history of colonialism: a history of domination, exploitation, and marginalization. The problem she points at has several ethical aspects. First, her basic sense of self-respect is violated; second, she does not perceive herself as equal to the “Western”; and third, her autonomy, i.e. her capability to determine her life and destiny, is put in question by her cultural heritage. Hence, the experience of being subject to cultural domination threatens her human dignity, equality, and autonomy. The story told by the master student illustrates what Rajeev Bhargava calls “epistemic injustice” (Bhargava 2013). Enduring social relations of the superior and subordinate has a tendency to create images of the Other and of oneself, and these images are shared by both the superior and the subordinate. We can notice this phenomenon in the history of class relations, gender relations, race relations, and colonial relations. In the history of colonialism, the master, the white, is looked up to and the servant, the slave, the colored, is someone to look down on. Unauthentifiziert | Heruntergeladen 01.10.19 07:33 UTC 3 Göran Collste Cultural Pluralism and Epistemic Injustice Cultural images stamped by colonialism have been analyzed in postcolonial studies (Said 2003, Loomba 2005). I here limit my discussion to Bhargava’s ideas of how colonialism implied epistemic injustice. Colonialism meant occupation of lands and a flow of resources from the colonies to the colonial powers, disempowering the former and enriching the latter. It also presupposed physical violence to keep the subaltern in place. However, colonialism implied more than that. Cultures and minds were also “colonized,” according to Bhargava. When trying to explain and theorize what colonization of cultures and minds means, Bhargava introduced the concept of “epistemic framework.” He defined it as follows: “An epistemic framework is a historically generated, collectively sustained system of meanings and significance, by reference to which a group understands and evaluates its individual and collective identity” (Bhargava 2013, 401). An epistemic framework helps us to interpret, understand, and categorize our impressions and experiences, so that they are manageable and possible to communicate and assess. Bhargava’s definition also emphasizes the importance of an epistemic framework for identity formation (individual and collective). A shared epistemic framework is important – indeed necessary – for any social group, such as ethnic, cultural or religious group. It provides basic hermeneutical tools for understanding the world and ourselves. An epistemic framework is also a hermeneutical resource for individuals to interpret and respond to new situations. According to Bhargava, epistemic injustice means that “concepts and categories” providing self-understanding and orientation are replaced or marginalized by a dominant power, in his case the colonizer. It was, Bhargava wrote, “... important/for the colonizer/to conquer not only the land and goods of the colonized but also their culture and minds” (Bhargava 2013, 414). How did this materialize? According to Bhargava, cultural and epistemic injustice can take different forms and the epistemic framework of the colonized was overthrown and lost by different processes. First, one form of epistemic injustice is when the dominant epistemic categories are the ones of the colonizers and the traditional, domestic, historical and cultural traditions become “scattered and diffused.” Bhargava wrote, “If the members of a group are denied access to their own culture then they suffer from cultural injustice” (Bhargava 2007, 218). Another form of epistemic injustice implies that the epistemic framework of the colonized is preserved, but it is considered of less worth and is inferior and marginalized in the society. A third form of epistemic injustice implies that the content of Unauthentifiziert | Heruntergeladen 01.10.19 07:33 UTC 4 Journal of Nationalism, Memory & Language Politics 13(2) the colonized epistemic framework is distorted. Bhargava gave an example: For the colonizer, the colonized appeared as a collective, a mass of people and not as individuals. They then transferred this view to the epistemic framework of the colonized, portraying it falsely as “collectivist” (Bhargava 2007, 231). This resulted in colonial policies “... based on the idea that the conception of an individual was simply absent among the colonized and that only group identity mattered in their traditions” (Bhargava 2013, 415). So, in sum, according to Bhargava, epistemic injustice implies that the local epistemic framework is dissolved, marginalized, or distorted. Why then was it important to conquer the minds of the colonized? It is because, in this way, they overtook views and values of the colonizers. They internalized them, and they then saw themselves as inferior and colonialism as beneficial and fair. Cultures, epistemic frameworks, and traditions are constantly changing. This is not the problem Bhargava wanted to highlight. No, the moral problem lies in the fact that the “... disapproval stems from the fact that this change is partly orchestrated by an authority with enormous political and economic power ...” (Bhargava 2015, 415). Thus, epistemic injustice was an integrated part of the colonial venture. Bhargava managed to provide a theoretical explanation of the experience of my master student. However, his texts also raised some questions. The first question is what exactly his argument refers to. Bhargava argued that as a consequence of colonialism, “indigenous cultures” were inferiorized, marginalized, and anonymized. This is a very general statement. One could question whether his analysis is equally valid for all kinds of cultural manifestations (academic, religious, literary, folkloristic, etc.) or if there are cultural zones that are more or less resilient and then, if there are cultural zones that could resist colonization better than others. Although the three continents Africa, Asia and Latin America were colonized, they were affected in different ways. For example, in contrast to Africa, India’s religious life seems to have been rather unaffected by British colonialism. In English school books for Indian children, Hinduism was represented in a distorted form and the representation was shaped by Christian presuppositions and categories (Balaji 2015). One could even say that Hinduism, as a religion, did not exist before it was so constructed by Western scholars. However still, the religious life of Indians, as well as customs and family life, was rather unaffected by colonialism. In Africa, on the other hand, the indigenous religions were to a large extent superseded by Christianity, although Christianity with an African stain. Unauthentifiziert | Heruntergeladen 01.10.19 07:33 UTC 5 Göran Collste Cultural Pluralism and Epistemic Injustice Furthermore, Bhargava argued that “... every group must have access to its own systems of meanings and interpretations ...” and they form “epistemic communities” (Bhargava 2013, 414). Bhargava’s theory needs clarifications. First, it is not clear what he means by a “group” and a “community.” For Bhargava, the colonization of India led to the epistemic domination of the colonizer and epistemic marginalization of indigenous Indian epistemic frameworks. Although it makes sense to speak of Indian indigenous cultures including not only Hindus but also Sikhs, Muslims, etc. having common ethos, habits, rituals, etc., the precolonial Indian society was also divided into castes, with – possibly – their own epistemic frameworks and forming their own epistemic communities.1 Thus, the idea of different epistemic communities does not only refer to different ethnic groups or nations but also to religious and social groups. While an epistemic framework refers to how a group “understands and evaluates its individual and collective identity,” it seems that, for example, also socialism, feminism, and Catholicism could be described as epistemic frameworks. This opens up for multiple and overlapping epistemic frameworks; for example, an Indian socialist refers to both an Indian and a socialist epistemic framework and an African Catholic to both an African and a Catholic epistemic framework. As we noticed, the idea of epistemic injustice presupposes relations of inequality and domination. Drawing on Philip Pettit’s analysis of political domination, Amandine Catala introduced the term “hermeneutical monopoly” when a minority in a society is “hermeneutically dominated by a majority.” Then, the minority lacks the resources to raise their voices in the public discourse and their views are dismissed by the majority (Catala 2015, 430). Hence, epistemic domination is one form of domination in parallel to other forms, such as economic and political. However, when Catala spoke of cultural and ethnical minorities in Western countries, Bhargava spoke of dominated majorities in colonized nations. Second, the idea that each group has its own “... system of meanings and interpretations ...” could be interpreted as implying a kind of relativism, because if each group has its own epistemic framework, it is difficult to see how they could communicate with each other: We know the world from our epistemic framework and you from yours and there is no way your interpretation could challenge ours. Without doubt, such a view would have some very problematic epistemic implications. However, Bhargava did not adhere to relativism because he also argued for the possibility of “biculturalism,” which means a “potentially common tradition.” Yes, he even foresaw “... the renewal of western traditions by non-western 1 See Fricker (2007) and Catala (2015) for analyses of epistemic dominations within societies. Unauthentifiziert | Heruntergeladen 01.10.19 07:33 UTC 6 Journal of Nationalism, Memory & Language Politics 13(2) people ...” (Bhargava 2013, 416-417). Hence, epistemic frameworks differ and overlap and communication is possible. In fact, there are reasons to believe that the Indian and Western traditions can co-exist and even integrate. Liberal ideas inspired the leaders of the new nation after independence from Britain, in particular Nehru who said “I am the last Englishman to rule in India.” Progress and Cultural Change Bhargava argued that colonialism implied that local cultures were marginalized. But are not cultures normally in a state of constant change? When we look at history, we find many examples of how one culture has been superseded by another. Is that always something to regret? Perhaps, the new culture is preferable? Was it for example a misfortune that Christianity superseded the Roman religion in the first centuriesy AD or that Islam superseded the Arabic religions in the sixth to seventh centuries? What was lost and what was gained? Did perhaps the new religion and culture offer an enhanced collective identity and existential security compared to the old ones? In line with Charles Taylor, one could presume that cultures have intrinsic value. He wrote: “... it is reasonable to suppose that cultures that have provided the horizon of meaning for large numbers of human beings, of diverse characters and temperaments, over a long period of time – that have, in other words, articulated their sense of the good, the holy, the admirable – are almost certain to have something that deserves our admiration and respect, even if it is accompanied by much that we have to abhor and reject.” (Taylor 1994, 72-73). On the other hand, even if we acknowledge the intrinsic value of cultures, it does not necessarily mean that all cultures have equal value. Brian Barry wrote: “... some cultures ... are better than others: more just, more free, more enlightened, and generally better adapted to human flourishing” (Barry 2001, 267). So, following Taylor, cultures are valuable because they provide “horizons of meaning,” but – as Barry argued – some are more valuable than others due to their capacity to make humans flourish. So, what is then morally wrong with epistemic injustice? Let me suggest the following answer. Epistemic injustice 1. implies that a culture is forced to subjection; 2. implies that the dominated culture is disrespected and considered as inferior; 3. implies a threat to the dominated people’s epistemic framework, collective identity, and existential security; and 4. implies an enduring sense of inferiority among the adherents of the old culture. Unauthentifiziert | Heruntergeladen 01.10.19 07:33 UTC 7 Göran Collste Cultural Pluralism and Epistemic Injustice So, epistemic injustice implies force and subjection. If a culture is valuable while it provides its adherents with instruments to interpret, understand, and provide meaning to their existence and, also in Taylor’s terms, articulate a sense of the good and holy, epistemic injustice is also morally wrong while it means an infringement of these valuable instruments and states of mind. Given that Bhargava’s description of the colonization of epistemic frameworks is correct, the indigenous cultures were dominated by force and were considered inferior, and the consequences were a loss of collective identity and a sense of existential insecurity among the colonized people. This sense of inferiority is enduring. Hence, the moral problem with epistemic injustice in the wake of colonialism is that it implied an enduring dominance and a sense of inferiority among the subaltern. Globalization and Epistemic Injustice Is then epistemic injustice in Bhargava’s sense a phenomenon of the colonial past – although with enduring consequences? Today, we live in an age traced by globalization. The meaning and impact of globalization are much discussed, and I will only focus on some aspects. To the present, globalization is not characterized by equality and reciprocity. Many facets of globalization mean the dominance of powerful economic organizations and multinational companies and a Westernization or Americanization of cultures and values. From this perspective, globalization implies neocolonization of cultures and minds. Globalization implies epistemic injustice in various forms, and I will distinguish between an apparent and a subtle form. The apparent form is illustrated by the global implementation of intellectual property rights, which is an example of globalization of parochial Western values at the expense of local and indigenous. Let me explain with the help of an example. One feature of the last decades’ globalization is the global commercialization of all sorts of goods, including medicines, herbs, and seeds. This was manifested by the so-called Agreement on Trade-Related Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights (TRIPS) agreement in 1994. According to the TRIPS agreement, intellectual property such as medicines and genetic material should be protected globally, and the TRIPS agreement was institutionalized when ratification of TRIPS became a condition for membership of the World Trade Organization (WTO). One of the controversial aspects of the global intellectual property regime is the extension of property rights to cover also traditional knowledge In a Unauthentifiziert | Heruntergeladen 01.10.19 07:33 UTC 8 Journal of Nationalism, Memory & Language Politics 13(2) number of cases, plants and herbs used for ages by traditional communities and indigenous peoples have been patented by Western firms. Here, traditional knowledge and communal ownership come into conflict with privatization and property rights. This value conflict is an example of when globalization means the domination of Western values at the expense of the values of weaker and more vulnerable communities and people (Shiva 2001, Commission 2002, Anderson 2015). Through the many ways that Western ideals are permeating the world through adverts, news media, and Hollywood films, globalization also implies a subtler form of cultural injustice. Here, the Western ideals of beauty, life style, and consumption are becoming global norms, which on the receiving side of the globe may lead to a contempt for one’s own culture and tradition. As a consequence, many women in Africa and Asia are whitening their skin and straightening their hair to live up to the Western ideals of beauty. According to a report from the University of Cape Town, 77% of women in Nigeria and 35% of women in South Africa use skin lighteners (http://www.bbc.com/ news/world-africa-20444798). So, what then are the remedies for epistemic injustice in the past and how can we avoid that also globalization will imply epistemic injustice? First and probably most important is that intellectuals in the countries who are subjects of epistemic injustice rediscover their own intellectual and epistemic traditions. This is also Bhargava’s strategy. In his ambition to rediscover the Indian tradition in political theory, he studied the edicts of the progressive Emperor Asoka from the third century BC. Similarly, African philosophers are developing the idea of Ubuntu, which expresses deep values of community in the African tradition (Metz and Gaie 2010). When commenting on the discussion of global justice, the Indian theorist Aakash Singh wrote: “[...] as the global justice debate amplifies unreflexively this increasingly discredited tendency of the wider social sciences to favour the epistemology and centrality of Anglo-American political theory/ theorists, generally excluding non-western voices from participation. Here, the term ‘global’ seems to signify outward expansion from the center; our attempt to extend our conception/demands of justice to them. Many non-western scholars, therefore, see the global justice debate as a recapitulation of the characteristic practices and attitudes of colonial liberalism” (Aakash 2014). What can we who are ancestors of the colonizers and who represent the global rich do today? How can we avoid “one-directional” communication, and how Unauthentifiziert | Heruntergeladen 01.10.19 07:33 UTC 9 Göran Collste Cultural Pluralism and Epistemic Injustice can we avoid epistemic injustice in the wake of globalization? As philosophers, Nancy Fraser and Axel Honneth have emphasized, “recognition” is a central concept here. Fraser wrote, “Misrecognition ... means social subordination in the sense of being prevented from participating as a peer in social life” (Fraser 2001, p.24). Misrecognition seems to be one condition for epistemic injustice. Hence, the social subordination of the Other could be overcome by recognition, i.e. to ensure that everyone has an equal say in conversations and dialogs. Listening to the Other follows from recognition. To listen is more than to hear. Michael Purdy defined listening as “... the active and dynamic process of attending, perceiving, interpreting, remembering, and responding to the expressed (verbal and nonverbal) needs, concerns, and information offered by other human beings” (Purdy 1991). Listening is a crucial condition for communication and a requirement for reciprocity, i.e. for “fair terms of cooperation” to quote Rawls (Rawls 1993, 16). Avoiding Parochialism As Aakash reminds us, in order to remedy for the colonial past and avoid epistemic injustice in the present, we have to reconsider the way we philosophize about global justice and international relations. In The Law of Peoples (1999), which is a treaty on international relations and justice, John Rawls took much efforts in developing a theory characterized by non-parochialism, meaning that the theory should avoid cultural biases and one-sidedness and instead accept pluralism and respect different traditions of how a society is formed. Already in his work Political Liberalism from 1993, Rawls distanced himself from a view of justice that universalizes western liberal values. He admits that his own theory of justice from 1971 suffers from this limitation. For example, the principle of moral autonomy developed in A Theory of Justice “... fails to satisfy the criterion of reciprocity required of reasonable political principles ...” (Rawls 1996, xlv). As an alternative, in Political Liberalism, he developed a theory of reasonable pluralism and justification of a political conception of justice based on an “overlapping consensus” of different – what he called – “comprehensive doctrines,” and comprehensive liberalism is one of them (ibid xlii). This implies that basic political institutions and rights are justified by all reasonable doctrines, although the reasons will differ between different doctrines. In Political Liberalism, Rawls’s aim was to develop criteria of justification of a theory of justice in plural societies. The aim of The Law of Peoples (1999) was to develop a theory of international relations in a plural world, and Rawls Unauthentifiziert | Heruntergeladen 01.10.19 07:33 UTC 10 Journal of Nationalism, Memory & Language Politics 13(2) raises the question how to achieve an inclusive Society of Peoples, i.e. a global community of peoples who cooperate and live peacefully together. According to Rawls, not only liberal peoples but also – what he called – “decent hierarchical peoples” are full members of the Society of Peoples. He takes the conceived Islamic people Kazanistan as his case in point. Islam is the favored religion, and only Muslims can have governmental positions. Other religions are tolerated, and their believers have civic rights. They are also included in a “decent consultation hierarchy,” and they are able to influence the political decisions from this position (Rawls 1999, 75-77). However, Kazanistan deviates in important respects from liberal ideals. The contrast between a cosmopolitan, liberal global order and the Society of Peoples that Rawls favors became clear when Rawls discussed human rights. In The Law of Peoples, Rawls only included “urgent human rights,” i.e. freedom from slavery, liberty of conscience and security of ethnic groups from mass murder and genocide. However, he did not include equal individual rights or liberal democracy (ibid, 78-81). The reason as he explained it is that “Human rights, as thus understood, cannot be rejected as peculiarly liberal or special to the Western tradition. They are not politically parochial” (ibid, 65). Rawls’s theory has been the target of critique by some liberals. Why, they ask, should we be satisfied with anything less than a society that implements full and universal human rights, and why should we in the long run tolerate political systems that are hierarchical and that distinguish between different ethnical and religious groups with respect to rights of influence? Why should non-Muslim citizens in Kazanistan accept the role as secondary members of their society? (Li 1995, Nickel 2006) These critical questions are indeed challenging. On the other hand, with Bhargava’s critique of epistemic injustice in mind, there are good reasons for Rawls’s position. In view of the history of colonialism – and the present globalization – we should be more cautious to assume that Western values, Western political systems, and Western political principles are universally valid and applicable. We must acknowledge that there are other political cultures and traditions that are acceptable and worthy of respect. Following Rawls, this acceptance of different political traditions does not mean that liberals should abstain from working for extension of human rights in any society they live in; only that liberalism is not a necessary requirement for inclusion in the Society of Peoples, the global community. This does not imply that a wider conception of human rights necessarily mirrors a Western or liberal comprehensive doctrine. The main human rights treaties have been ratified by a large majority of the nations of the world, and Unauthentifiziert | Heruntergeladen 01.10.19 07:33 UTC 11 Göran Collste Cultural Pluralism and Epistemic Injustice as a German philosopher Heiner Bielefeldt remarked, human rights can be understood “... as the centre of a cross-cultural ‘overlapping consensus’ on basic normative standards in our increasingly multi-cultural societies.” No, what Rawls’s proposal might avoid is a “... cultural essentialist occupation” of human rights (Bielefeldt 2016, 86). Should we then accept this more limited human rights conception as the ground for a Society of Peoples or should we assume a broader liberal conception of human rights? It is not an easy choice. However, it seems to me that Rawls’s position avoids that faults of the past are repeated in the present. We should bear in mind that Rawls does not accept any kind of hierarchical societies. They have to live up to the conditions of respecting urgent human rights, i.e. respect for human beings’ freedom of thought and organization and their right to influence the government (although in different ways and perhaps within different institutions). Conclusion The aim of this essay was to discuss the meaning of epistemic and cultural injustice and how to overcome it in the present age characterized by globalization and the encounter of different cultures. The history of colonialism is a history of enduring cultural domination and epistemic injustice. Epistemic injustice is prima facie problematic from a moral point of view, while it implies domination, disrespect, a sense of inferiority and erosion of dominated people’s epistemic framework, collective identity, and existential security. Today’s possibilities of cultural encounters and emerging multicultural societies offer a potential for learning, cultural enrichment and plurality. However, the realization of this potential presupposes that we recognize the others and listen to their beliefs and values. As Rawls showed, avoiding parochialism is both necessary and possible in present plural societies. References Anderson, Jane.2015. Indigenous Knowledge and Intellectual Property Rights. International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, 2nd edition, Volume 11, Elsevier. pp 769- 779. Balaji, Murali. 2018. “The Colonized Mind. Thoughts on colonialism, Christianity and the relinquishment of Hindu consciousness.” Hinduism Today. https://www.hinduismtoday. com/modules/smartsection/item.php?itemid=3103. Barry, Brian. 2002. Culture and Equality. An Egalitarian Critique of Multiculturalism. Har- vard: Harvard University Press. Unauthentifiziert | Heruntergeladen 01.10.19 07:33 UTC 12 Journal of Nationalism, Memory & Language Politics 13(2) Bhargava, Rajeev. 2007. “How Should We Respond to the Cultural Injustices of Colonial- ism?” In Reparations: Interdisciplinary Inquiries, edited by J. Miller and R. Kumar. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bhargava, Rajeev. 2013. “Overcoming the Epistemic Injustice of Colonialism.” Global Policy 4 (4): 413-417. Bielefeldt, Heiner. 2016. “‘Western’ versus ‘Islamic’ Human Rights Conceptions? A Critique of Cultural Essentialism in the Discussion on Human Rights,” In Ethics and Communica- tion. Global Perspectives, edited by G. Collste. London: Rowman & Littlefield International. Catala, Amandine. 2015. “Democracy, Trust, and Epistemic Injustice.” The Monist, 98 (4): 424-440. Collste, Göran. 2015. Global Rectificatory Justice. Basingstoke: Palgrave. Fricker, Miranda. 2007. Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press Kymlicka, Will. 1996. Multicultural Citizenship A Liberal Theory of Minority Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press Metz, Thaddeus and Gaie Joseph, B. R. 2010. “The African Ethic of Ubuntu/Botho: Implica- tions for Research on Morality.” Journal of Moral Education 39 (3): 273-290. Nickel, James. 2006. “Are Human Rights Mainly implemented by Intervention?” In Rawls’s Law of Peoples. A Realistic Utopia?, edited by R. Martin and D. Reidy. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing. Rawls, John. 1996. Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press. Rawls, John. 1999. The Law of Peoples. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Sen, Amartya. 1999. Development as Freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Singh, Aakash. 2013. “Deparochializing the Global Justice Debate, Starting with Indian Po- litical Theory.” Global Policy 4 (4): 418-419 Li, Xiarong. 1995. “A Critique of Rawls’s Freestanding Justice.” Journal of Applied Philosophy, 12 (3): 263-271. Taylor, Charles. 1994. “The Politics of Recognition.” In Multiculturalism: Examining the Poli- tics of Recognition, edited by Amy Gutman. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Unauthentifiziert | Heruntergeladen 01.10.19 07:33 UTC work_irdykv4m6nevbnan33xjypeui4 ---- International Journal of Recent Technology and Engineering (IJRTE) International Journal of Recent Technology and Engineering (IJRTE) ISSN: 2277-3878, Volume-8 Issue-2S10, September 2019 647 Published By: Blue Eyes Intelligence Engineering & Sciences Publication Retrieval Number: B11150982S1019/2019©BEIESP DOI:10.35940/ijrte.B1115.0982S1019  Abstract: Perceptions of organizational justice constitute an important heuristic in organizational decision-making, as research relates it to job satisfaction, turnover, leadership, organizational citizenship, organizational commitment, trust, customer satisfaction, job performance, employee theft, role breadth, alienation, and leader-member exchange. The public sector in UAE is the focus of this paper. Applying the concept of organizational justice (distributive justice, procedural justice, interactional justice) to examine the effect of it on employees’ satisfaction. The data was collected from 452 officers from 7 sectors in the ministry of interior in UAE and analysed using structural equation modelling via SmartPLS 3.0. There were three main results: first, distributive justice has a positive impact on job satisfaction; second, procedural justice is significantly predicting job satisfaction; third, interactional justice has a significant impact on job satisfaction. The proposed model explained 33.7% of the variance in job satisfaction. Theoretical and practical implications are also provided. Keywords: Organizational justice; distributive justice; procedural justice; interactional justice; job satisfaction. I. INTRODUCTION The effects of globalization, and competition on an international level, have rendered the recruitment, maintenance, and organization of resources, decisive factors for success in the public sector domain. In the services sector, it is acknowledged that the management of human resources, in particular, is a crucial factor. This is attributed to the fact that the services offered, and the supplier of these services, are, to a large extent, interconnected. In this regard, enhancing an employee’s job satisfaction, dedication to the organization and motivation, will serve to promote his/her extra-role behaviour, by way of organizational citizenship behaviour. This, in turn, will contribute towards an improved standing of the public sector organization concerned, in terms of competitiveness. The close relationship between job satisfaction, and performance, is particularly evident in the service industry. Revised Manuscript Received on September 25, 2019 Rashed ALNEYADI, Faculty of Business and Accountancy, Lincoln University College, Selangor, Malaysia Mohammed NUSARI, Faculty of Business and Accountancy, Lincoln University College, Selangor, Malaysia Ali Ameen, Faculty of Business and Accountancy, Lincoln University College, Selangor, Malaysia Amiya Bhaumik, Faculty of Business and Accountancy, Lincoln University College, Selangor, Malaysia In the field of organizational research, justice perceptions are viewed as explanatory variables. Organizational justice defines the perspective of individuals (or groups), with regards to the impartiality of an organization’s conduct towards them, and the behavioural response of these individuals (or groups) towards this perspective. The extant literature classifies the three aspects of justice perceptions as distributive justice, procedural justice and interactional justice. It has been established that perceived organizational justice is a significant antecedent to organizational citizenship behaviour. While the impact of justice perceptions on work attitude and work behaviour is well-documented in western literature, the same cannot be said for the situation in the United Arab Emirates (UAE). Here, studies focusing on this subject matter have, unfortunately, been rather few and far between. II. LITERATURE REVIEW A. Job Satisfaction (JS) Job satisfaction has to do with the attitudes or opinions of employees regarding their work specifically or their work setting as a whole, and their general sentiment as regards to their job requirements. The origins of the job satisfaction concept can be traced to an investigation conducted in the 1920s, which came to be known as the Hawthorne studies. The outcomes from this endeavour revealed that the emotions of a worker, has a significant effect on his/her behaviour at work. The job satisfaction and productivity levels of an employee are determined principally by his/her social and psychological circumstances. Job satisfaction refers to an individual’s response to his/her working situation. This response arises from a comparison between the real situation, and the situation that is anticipated, craved and required. Personal in nature, this response is indicative of the degree of contentment an employee experiences with regards to his/her job. B. Organizational Justice (OJ) Distributive justice has its roots in the equity theory. This theory focuses on the perception of a worker concerning his/her treatment, in comparison to other workers. The equity theory asserts that the contributions of employees towards the organization come in the form of education, effort and experience, among others. Impact of Organizational Justice (Distributive Justice, Procedural Justice, and Interactional Justice) on Job Satisfaction Rashed Alneyadi, Mohammed Nusari, Ali Ameen, Amiya Bhaumik Impact of Organizational Justice (Distributive Justice, Procedural Justice, and Interactional Justice) on Job Satisfaction 648 Published By: Blue Eyes Intelligence Engineering & Sciences Publication Retrieval Number: B11150982S1019/2019©BEIESP DOI:10.35940/ijrte.B1115.0982S1019 In view of these contributions, employees are entitled to returns in the way of salaries and promotions. The perceived ratio of what an employee receives as a result of his/her work, in comparison to the degree of effort put into the said work, serves to ascertain whether the situation is one of equity, or inequity. Put plainly, workers anticipate a response from the management that commensurate with their level of contribution in terms of work. Procedural justice represents another route towards the assessment of impartiality with regards to decisions concerning remunerations, or decisions related to administrative issues. This concept contemplates the approach employed to arrive at these decisions. Procedural justice emphasizes on the perceived fairness, of the course adopted to decide on the severity of the penalty, or the scale of the remuneration doled out. Thus, the approach adopted to realize the results, may turn out to be of more significance, than the results themselves. Interactional justice defines the degree of perceived fairness regarding the manner in which an employee is cared for by the establishment. Unlike procedural justice, the interaction occurring in interactional justice is of a more informal nature. It has to do with the level of integrity, compassion and respect displayed by management, during communications with employees. Procedural justice differs from interactional justice in that with the latter, the emphasis is on perceived justice, or injustice. Several investigations have delved into the connection between the abovementioned modes of organizational justice, and their impact on work issues such as turnover intention, organizational commitment, organizational citizenship behaviour and job satisfaction. This led to proposal of the hypotheses as below: H1. Distributive justice significantly has a positive impact on job satisfaction. H2. Procedural justice significantly has a positive impact on job satisfaction. H3. Interactional justice significantly has a positive impact on job satisfaction. Figure 1 shows the proposed study model which was derived from the social exchange theory and contains three independent variables (distributive justice, procedural justice, and interactional justice) and one dependent variable (job satisfaction). Fig. 1 The proposed model III. RESEARCH DESIGN AND METHODOLOGY A. Instrument Development Equipped with information available in relevant literature, we applied a multi-item Likert scale for a 23-item questionnaire. As recommended in previous investigations, the constructs were gauged with the use of a 5-point Likert scale [1-3], with 5 signifying ‘Strongly Agree’ and 1 signifying ‘Strongly Disagree’. Taking into consideration the fully Arab-speaking composition of respondents, the items in the questionnaire were accurately translated from English to Arabic. Back translation, a procedure frequently applied in cross-cultural surveys, was employed for this purpose. We referred to previous studies for the gauging of the variables (Appendix A). B. Data Collection Between April, 2018 and August, 2018, 600 self-administered questionnaires were handed out to government workers. Of these, 480 were returned, and 452 were considered for our survey. This sample size is similar to that used by Krejcie & Morgan (1970) [4] for their study in this area. Our realized response rate of 60.42% can be deemed excellent, when compared to those of previous investigations, documented in relevant literature. Of the 28 removed questionnaires, 21 were found to have omitted answers to more than 15% of the questions, three were outliers, and 4 came with a straight lining. IV. Data Analysis and Results The SmartPLS 3.0 software was used to examine our model through partial least squares (PLS) variance-based structural equation modelling (VB-SEM). A two-stage analytical procedure was utilized for (a) evaluating the measurement model (validity and reliability), and (b) evaluating the structural model (hypothesized relationships analysis). A. Descriptive analysis Job satisfaction score the highest with mean 3.356 out of 5.0, with a standard deviation of 1.148. Distributive justice score the lowest with mean 2.991 out of 5.0, with a standard deviation of 0.944, as Table 1 shows. B. Measurement Model Assessment The measurement model was assessed for construct reliability and validity. The values of every single Cronbach’s alpha surpassed the targeted value of 0.7 [5]. Additionally, the test for construct reliability revealed that every composite reliability (CR) value, also went beyond 0.7 [6]. Factor loadings were used to evaluate indicator reliability. Except for IJ5 and IJ6, the values recorded exceeded the sought after value of 0.7. IJ5 and IJ6 were subsequently discarded from the scale, due to depleted loading values. Convergent validity was evaluated by way of average variance extracted (AVE). The values attained topped the objective value of 0.50. These evaluation results are exhibited in Table 1. Table 1: Measurement assessment results International Journal of Recent Technology and Engineering (IJRTE) ISSN: 2277-3878, Volume-8 Issue-2S10, September 2019 649 Published By: Blue Eyes Intelligence Engineering & Sciences Publication Retrieval Number: B11150982S1019/2019©BEIESP DOI:10.35940/ijrte.B1115.0982S1019 Constructs Item Loading (> 0.5) M SD α (> 0.7) CR (> 0.7) AVE (> 0.5) Distributive Justice (DJ) DJ1 DJ2 DJ3 DJ4 DJ5 0.791 0.877 0.894 0.904 0.877 2.991 0.944 0.919 0.939 0.756 Procedural Justice (PJ) PJ1 PJ2 PJ3 PJ4 PJ5 PJ6 0.916 0.837 0.908 0.889 0.829 0.885 3.131 1.043 0.940 0.953 0.771 Interactional Justice (IJ) IJ1 IJ2 IJ3 IJ4 IJ5 IJ6 IJ7 IJ8 IJ9 0.853 0.789 0.833 0.786 Deleted Deleted 0.844 0.713 0.709 2.997 0.729 0.900 0.921 0.626 Job Satisfaction (JS) JS1 JS2 JS3 0.934 0.927 0.927 3.356 1.148 0.921 0.950 0.864 Note: M=Mean; SD=Standard Deviation, α= Cronbach’s alpha; CR = Composite Reliability, AVE = Average Variance Extracted. Key: DJ: Distributive Justice, PJ: Procedural Justice, IJ: Interactional Justice, JS: Job Satisfaction The discriminant validity of the measurement model was assessed through cross-loadings and the Fornell-Larcker criterion. Cross-loadings are typically the initial step for tests on the discriminant validity of indicators. The requirements for discriminant validity in our model were considered met, as the indicators’ outer loadings on a construct, surpassed its cross-loadings with other constructs. The evaluation results for discriminant validity through cross-loadings are displayed in Table 2. Table 2: Results of discriminant validity by the cross loading DJ PJ IJ JS DJ1 0.791 0.503 0.417 0.357 DJ2 0.877 0.596 0.515 0.416 DJ3 0.894 0.618 0.530 0.437 DJ4 0.904 0.640 0.609 0.500 DJ5 0.877 0.612 0.515 0.418 PJ1 0.635 0.916 0.576 0.494 PJ2 0.549 0.837 0.499 0.389 PJ3 0.612 0.908 0.569 0.503 PJ4 0.638 0.889 0.566 0.469 PJ5 0.532 0.829 0.522 0.412 PJ6 0.637 0.885 0.553 0.471 IJ1 0.477 0.485 0.853 0.398 IJ2 0.401 0.403 0.789 0.344 IJ3 0.435 0.443 0.833 0.365 IJ4 0.407 0.414 0.786 0.352 IJ7 0.488 0.503 0.844 0.411 IJ8 0.509 0.566 0.713 0.404 IJ9 0.561 0.592 0.709 0.450 JS1 0.457 0.483 0.453 0.934 Impact of Organizational Justice (Distributive Justice, Procedural Justice, and Interactional Justice) on Job Satisfaction 650 Published By: Blue Eyes Intelligence Engineering & Sciences Publication Retrieval Number: B11150982S1019/2019©BEIESP DOI:10.35940/ijrte.B1115.0982S1019 JS2 0.473 0.483 0.463 0.927 JS3 0.446 0.492 0.473 0.927 Key: DJ: Distributive Justice, PJ: Procedural Justice, IJ: Interactional Justice, JS: Job Satisfaction . Table 3 shows the results for discriminant validity acquired through the Fornell-Larcker criterion. As can be gathered from this table, the square root of the AVEs on the diagonals (portrayed in bold) are higher than the correlations between constructs (matching row and column values). This indicates a clearer linkage between the constructs and their individual indicators, as compared to the other constructs in the model. A similar outcome was seen in which it was indicative of superior discriminant validity. The correlation of the exogenous constructs in our study was observed to be below 0.85 (Awang, 2014). In view of the above, the discriminant validity for all the constructs in our investigation can be deemed adequately met. Table 3: Results of discriminant validity by Fornell-Larcker criterion DJ IJ JS PJ DJ 0.869 IJ 0.601 0.791 JS 0.493 0.498 0.930 PJ 0.686 0.625 0.523 0.878 Note: Diagonals represent the square root of the average variance extracted while the other entries represent the correlation s. Key: DJ: Distributive Justice, PJ: Procedural Justice, IJ: Interactional Justice, JS: Job Satisfaction C. Structural Model Assessment The structural model can be tested by computing beta (β), R², and the corresponding t-values via a bootstrapping procedure with a resample of 5,000. Key: DJ: Distributive Justice, PJ: Procedural Justice, IJ: Interactional Justice, JS: Job Satisfaction Fig 2: PLS algorithm results Figure 2 and Table 4 depict the structural model assessment, showing the results of the hypothesis tests, with 3 out of the 3 hypotheses are supported. Distributive justice, procedural justice, and interactional justice significantly predict job satisfaction. Hence, H1, H2, and H3 are accepted with (tp <0.01), (tp <0.001), and (tp <0.001) respectively. The strength of the relationship between exogenous and endogenous constructs are measured by the standardised path coefficients, which in this case show that the direct effects of procedural justice on job satisfaction is much stronger than the influence of other variables. Thirty-four percent of the variance in job satisfaction is explained by distributive justice, procedural justice, and interactional justice. The values of R² have an acceptable level of explanatory power, indicating a substantial model. International Journal of Recent Technology and Engineering (IJRTE) ISSN: 2277-3878, Volume-8 Issue-2S10, September 2019 651 Published By: Blue Eyes Intelligence Engineering & Sciences Publication Retrieval Number: B11150982S1019/2019©BEIESP DOI:10.35940/ijrte.B1115.0982S1019 Table 4: Structural assessment results Hypothesis Relationship Std Beta Std Error t-value p-value Decision R² H1 DJ→JS 0.180 0.064 2.825 0.002 Supported 0.34 H2 PJ→JS 0.256 0.065 3.909 0.000 Supported H3 IJ→ JS 0.230 0.066 3.500 0.000 Supported Key: DJ: Distributive Justice, PJ: Procedural Justice, IJ: Interactional Justice, JS: Job Satisfaction V. DISCUSSION Based on the proposed model, this study improves the understanding of the role played by organizational justice in terms of distributive justice, procedural justice, and interactional justice in predicting job satisfaction among employees in government sector in UAE, and highlights relevant implications. The discussions are further detailed in the following. The study found that distributive justice positively affects job satisfaction among employees in government sector in UAE, this is supported by previous studies [7]. It is explained by the fact that the more the employee receive fair rewards with regard to responsibilities, education level, efforts, stress and the tension created by the job, and with regard to the fulfilled responsibilities. The more the employees are satisfied with the job and with the work he/she is doing. Furtherm the results revealed that procedural justice has a significant influence on job satisfaction among employees in government sector in UAE which is also supported by previous studies [8]. It is explained by the fact that the more the supervisors are neutral about decision making, listening to others before decision making, gather the right information related to the topic of decision making, give additional information when necessary, have their decisions implemented to everyone consistently, and they have the right to deny or accept the decision. The more the employees is satisfied with the job and with the work he/she is doing. Lastly, it was also found that interactional justice significantly predicts job satisfaction among employees in government sector in UAE, this is supported by previous studies. It is explained by the fact that the more the supervisors are polite and concerned for decisions about employee’s job, respectful and careful about decisions about employee’s job, sensitive to personal needs, give importance to personal rights, inform the employee about the implications of the decisions, have Logical explanations for decisions. The more the employees is satisfied with the job and with the work he/she is doing. VI. IMPLICATIONS, LIMITATIONS AND FUTURE DIRECTIONS The results highlighted that organizational justice a strong impact on its employees' overall job satisfaction because the organizational justice provides a fair treatment of the employees. Given that each individual highly receives the organizational justice they will be ensured that they will take his/her right in the salary, career development, compensation, job security, respect, and appreciation. As all the organization's resources have been distributed fairly as well as these resourced must be distributed based on proper and fair procedures and the interactional justice - including respect and appreciation - is essential to be achieved, admittedly, their employees are highly likely to develop great job satisfaction. Given that the employees' job satisfaction is greatly associated with the organizational justice, the top management in the organization has to measure the employees' perceptions of the organizational justice. The managers can evaluate these perceptions by using the current study's questionnaire. If the managers find the employees' feelings of the organizational justice are low, however, they developed high-quality distributive justice, procedural justice, and interactional justice. They should find the reasons of low perceptions of the organizational justice, perhaps the implications of these practices are not achieved properly. Despite its strengths, this study has a limitation that also suggest areas for future research. This study was limited by police officers of the interior ministry in UAE. In the future research, the researcher suggests to investigate the study hypotheses in other geographical areas, as well as, the sample should include public and private sector to increase the generalization. VII. CONCLUSION By way of conclusion, the main objective of this study was to deepen our understanding of the relationship between distributive justice, procedural justice and interactional justice, and job satisfaction. The perspectives of social exchange theory were applied to further develop our understanding of the link between the study variables. It has provided evidence from leading scholars in the field on the notion of ‘organizational justice’ and how it is essential to build the employees satisfaction. Regardless of various constraints to the study, the results have been encouraging, as it has managed to throw some lights on organizational justice in the public sector in the UAE. The results revealed that the three hypotheses are significant. The independent variables significantly explain 33.7% of job satisfaction. The implications of this study have been deliberated, some directions for future research have been suggested. Impact of Organizational Justice (Distributive Justice, Procedural Justice, and Interactional Justice) on Job Satisfaction 652 Published By: Blue Eyes Intelligence Engineering & Sciences Publication Retrieval Number: B11150982S1019/2019©BEIESP DOI:10.35940/ijrte.B1115.0982S1019 APPENDIX Appendix A Instrument for varibles Varible Measure Source Distributive Justice (DJ) DJ1: I receive fair rewards with regard to responsibilities in my organization. DJ2: I receive fair rewards with regard to education level in my organization. DJ3: I receive fair rewards with regard to the efforts in my organization DJ4: I receive fair rewards with regard to stress and the tension created by the job. DJ5: I receive fair rewards with regard to the fulfilled responsibilities in my organization. Procedural Justice (PJ) PJ1: My supervisor is neutral about decision making. PJ2: My supervisor is listening to others before decision making. PJ3: My supervisor is collecting the right information related to the topic of decision making. PJ4: My supervisor is giving additional information when necessary PJ5: My supervisor’s decisions are implemented to everyone consistently. PJ6: My supervisor has the right to deny or accept the decision. [10] Interactional Justice (IJ) IJ1: My supervisor is polite and concerned for decisions about my job. IJ2: My supervisor is respectful and careful about decisions about my job. IJ3: My supervisor is sensitive to personal needs for decisions about my job. IJ4: My supervisor is sincere for decisions about my job. IJ5: My supervisor gives importance to personal rights for decisions about my job. IJ6: My supervisor’s implications of the decisions about my job is told to me. IJ7: My supervisor’s explanation for the decisions related to my job. IJ8: My supervisor has Logic explanations for decisions taken about my job. IJ9: My supervisor has a clear explanation for decisions related to my job. [10] Job Satisfaction (JS) JS1: All things considered, I am satisfied with my job. JS2: I like my job. JS3: I am generally satisfied with the work I do in this job. REFERENCES 1. O. Isaac, Z. Abdullah, T. Ramayah & M. Mutahar Ahmed, (2017). Examining the Relationship between Overall Quality, User Satisfaction and Internet Usage: An Integrated Individual, Technological, Organizational and Social Perspective. Asian Journal of Information Technology, 16(1), pp. 100–124. 2. O. Isaac, Z. Abdullah, T. Ramayah, A. M. Mutahar & I. Alrajawy, (2017). Towards a Better Understanding of Internet Technology Usage by Yemeni Employees in the Public Sector: An Extension of the Task-Technology Fit (TTF) Model. Research Journal of Applied Sciences, 12(2), pp. 205–223. 3. O. Isaac, Z. Abdullah, T. Ramayah, & A. M. Mutahar, (2017). Internet usage, user satisfaction, task-technology fit, and performance impact among public sector employees in Yemen. The International Journal of Information and Learning Technology, 34(3), pp. 210–241. 4. R. V Krejcie & D. W. Morgan, (1970). Determining sample size for research activities. Educational and Psychological Measurement, 38, pp. 607–610. 5. V. R. Kannana & K. C. Tan, (2005). Just in time, total quality management, and supply chain management: understanding their linkages and impact on business performance. Omega: The International Journal of Management Science, 33(2), pp. 153–162. 6. R. B. Kline, (2010). Principles and practice of structural equation modeling (3rd ed.). New York: The Guilford Press. 7. Wolfe, S. E., Rojek, J., Manjarrez, V. M., Jr., & Rojek, A. (2018). Why does organizational justice matter? Uncertainty management among law enforcement officers. Journal of Criminal Justice, 54, 20-29. 8. Middelkamp-Hup MA, Pathak MA, Parrado C, Goukassian D, Rius-Diaz F, Mihm MC, et al. Oral Polypodium leucotomos extract decreases ultraviolet-induced damage of human skin. J Am Acad Dermatol. 2004; 51, pp. 910–8. 9. M. Abdulrab, A. R. Zumrah, Q. Almaamari, A. N. Al-Tahitah, O. Isaac, & A. Ameen, (2018). The Role of Psychological Empowerment as a Mediating Variable between Perceived Organizational Support and Organizational Citizenship Behaviour in Malaysian Higher Education Institutions. International Journal of Management and Human Science (IJMHS) Vol. 2. 10. Palaiologos, Anastasios & Papazekos, Panagiotis & Panayotopoulou, Leda. (2011). Organizational justice and employee satisfaction in performance appraisal. Journal of European Industrial Training. 35. 826-840. work_irhpkmrsi5gbpl2l3ayttftoy4 ---- 0701.indd 5 U svom radu autorka iznosi osnovne teori-jske postavke i diskusije o praktičnoj pri-meni restorativne pravde. Razmatra pitanja uvođenja i primene restorativne pravde u smislu postizanja ravnoteže interesa žrtve, društvene za- jednice i delinkventa. Ovaj pojam se defi niše nabra- janjem određenih aktivnosti uz poštovanje izvesnih standarda i principa u primeni. Takođe, izdvojene su vrednosti kojima teži restorativna pravda. Deo rada posvećen je standardima za primenu restor- ativne pravde. Važna je usklađenost tih standarda sa međunarodno usvojenim dokumentima o zaštiti osnovnih ljudskih prava. Ključne reči: restorativna pravda, standardi, prin- cipi, retributivna pravda Uvod U današnjem kulturološkom određenju savre- menih društava, cilj i ishod postupanja usmereni su ka toleranciji različitosti, bilo da je ona etničke, rasne ili ekonomske prirode. Slogan „čini sve što želiš sve dok dozvoljavaš da ja činim ono što želim“ označava jasan stav ne-suđenja u odnosu na postupke drugih. Međutim, tolerancija često ne može sama po sebi da kreira, u smislu prom- ena, sadašnju situaciju i događaje u njoj i nekada nije jedino prihvatljivo rešenje. Tolerantan stav ljudi u postupanju neće izlečiti teškoće u jednom društvu, poput socijalne izolacije ili očaja ljudi. Za- to se treba usmeriti na ostvarenje opšte društvene dobrobiti koja se određuje kao „čitava mreža soci- jalnih uslova koji omogućavaju pojedincima i gru- pama ljudi da napreduju i žive punim humanim životom. Daleko od toga da svako bude prvenst- veno za sebe, već su svi odgovorni za sve“.1 (Cava- nagh, 2000) Filozofski pristup opšteg dobra nudi alternativnu viziju stvarnosti u kojoj živimo. Mir je centralno pitanje opšteg dobra, a oprost i po- mirenje su putevi kojima se dolazi do mira u sebi, porodici ili lokalnoj zajednici. Primena restorativne pravde u svakodnevnom životu je jedan od načina ostvarenja društvenog mira. Restorativna pravda naglašava značaj lečenja posledica zločina, uz uravnoteženo usmerenje ka učiniocu, žrtvi i zajed- nici, stvarajući osnov u zajedničkoj primeni prakse koja se ne može postići klasičnim retributivnim sistemom iz razloga što je on zasnovan na zakonu i kažnjavanju. Cilj ovoga rada upravo je u tome da domaćoj javnosti ukaže na značaj uvođenja i primene re- storativne pravde, kao i na osnovne standarde na kojima se ona zasniva. S obzirom na promene u pozitivnom krivičnom i porodičnom zakonodavst- vu kod nas, važno je da stručnjaci identifi kuju pro- 1 Ovo su reči koje je izgovorio sveštenik Jum Consedine, zastupnik restorativne pravde sa Novog Zelanda. Uspostavljanje standarda za restorativnu pravdu* Dr Miomira KOSTIĆ** * Prateći dostignuća teorije i prakse krivičnopravnog reagovanja na kriminalitet, u domaćem krivičnom zakonodavstvu došlo je do izvesnih promena koje ukazuju na postepeno, ali dosledno prihvatanje svih onih uslovno „novina“ koje prate uvođenje i primenu procesa restorativne pravde u nas. S druge strane, čak i zakonska rešenja koja izričito propisuju mogućnost primene procesa restorativne pravde nailaze na otpor, i stručne i opšte javnosti, gde se objektivni nedostatak podzakonskih akata često uzima kao subjektivni izgovor u neprimenjivanju pojedinih rešenja. Promene u krivičnom zakonodavstvu u odnosu na punoletne i maloletne učinioce krivičnih dela unose izvesne konkretne elemente restorativne pravde u domaći, tradicionalno retributivni krivičnopravni sistem. Ovaj rad je pokušaj da se ukaže na neka od navedenih pitanja i deo je rezultata istraživanja na projektu „Pristup pravosuđu – instrumenti za implementaciju evropskih standarda u pravni sistem Republike Srbije“, br. 149043D, koji fi nansira Ministarstvo nauke i zaštite životne sredine Republike Srbije. ** Miomira Kostić je vanredna profesorka na Pravnom fakultetu u Nišu, e-mail: gagam@medianis.net RESTORATIVNA PRAVDA I PRAVA ŽRTAVA TEMIDA Maj 2007, str 5-14 ISSN: 1450-6637 DOI: 10.2298/tem0701005K 6 ces restorativne pravde i vrste „putokaza“ koje će im u tome pomoći. Tako će vrednosti kojima teži restorativna pravda dobiti svoje utemeljenje u standardima, čija primena u restorativnom pro- cesu omogućava izbegavanje ili bar ublažavanje mogućih grešaka. Određenje restorativne pravde Sistem krivičnog pravosuđa, sprovodeći retrib- utivnu pravdu, usmeren je da odgovori na pitanja o tome koji je zakon prekršen, ko ga je prekršio i kako sankcionisati krivca tako da se postigne specijalna prevencija. Pristup restorativne pravde sastoji se u strategiji okupljanja i diskusije u okviru lokalne zajednice, okrenut je pojedincu i može se primeniti i u širim gradskim sredinama. Cilj je postizanje jedinstvenih rešenja koja su prihvatljiva za ljude u određenim okolnostima i s obzirom na kulturne prilike koje vladaju. Vremenom, u teorijs- kim raspravama i praktičnoj primeni, restorativna pravda, kao pojam i proces, dobila je značenje ključnog elementa društvene pravde. Restor- ativnoj pravdi pripisuje se sposobnost vraćanja pravde u društvenu zajednicu u kojoj je tradicio- nalni krivičnopravni sistem povezan sa merama opresije unutar zajednice. Te mere izriču organi formalne društvene kontrole u centralizovanom, statičnom krivičnom postupku koji svoje oprav- danje nalazi u opštoj, za sve građane dostupnoj pravdi (Kostić, 2005: 45). U teorijskim razmatranjima o standardima, vred- nostima i obezbeđivanju sprovođenja restorativne pravde često se ističe zanemarivanje socijalnih težnji i tradicije prilikom usvajanja ovog procesa. Restorativna pravda se nekada razmatra samo kao mogućnost ostvarivanja većeg obima prava žrtava pored utemeljenog krivičnopravnog sistema retrib- utivne pravde, a nekada opet kao ravnoteža između prava delinkvenata i prava žrtava. Ipak i pored izvesnih nesuglasica i nedoslednos- ti u sprovođenju, restorativna pravda, primenom svojih principa, obezbeđuje restituciju žrtava i društvene zajednice, promoviše reintegraciju delinkvenata i popravljanje odnosa između žrtve, delinkventa i društvene zajednice. U procesu re- storativne pravde predviđena je mogućnost da se delinkventna ponašanja dožive kao krajnje oz- biljna delanja prema kojima će se postupati bez povišene represije i isključivanja delinkvenata iz društvene zajednice, uz proces restitucije žrtava. Kako neki autori ističu, restorativna pravda daje iz- gled na izbegavanje tzv. “nultog iznosa”, pri čemu benefi cije žrtava pogađaju delinkventa, ne u nje- govim pravima, već u povećanom obimu obaveza zbog svog ponašanja (McEvoy i dr. 2002: 469). Različita udruženja građana, službe za pružanje društvenih usluga, škole, lokalna zajednica, zako- nodavni organi i odeljenja za prevenciju obavljaju najveći broj različitih aktivnosti u procesu restor- ativne pravde. Ove aktivnosti, vezane za razne oblasti društvenog života, povezuju zajednički elementi: lečenje, posredovanje između žrtve i učinioca, izvinjenje (osećanje stida) i reintegracija.2 Zato je prilikom defi nisanja restorativne pravde neophodno sadržajno objediniti sve ove pro- cese. Restorativna pravda se određuje kao „proces pomoću koga sve strane, koje su učestvovale u vršenju određenog krivičnog dela, zajedno nas- toje da savladaju posledice zločina i njegove im- plikacije u budućnosti” (Cavanagh, 1998: 24). Pitanjima restorativne pravde, u razvijenim zemljama sveta, bave se i crkvene zajednice. Tako Crkveni savet za pravdu i popravljanje (The Church Council on Justice and Corrections) koji okuplja je- danaest crkvenih zajednica Kanade, restorativnu pravdu opisuje kao “...omiljeno ime dato velikom broju različitih pristupa pravdi koji su se pojavili i koji teže isceliteljskim i uspešnijim odgovorima na zločin. Pošto postoji veliki broj različitih pris- tupa, ovi procesi pokušavaju da aktivno obje- dine učešće u svemu onome što je neposredno obuhvaćeno izvršenim zločinom. Svako treba da sasluša iskustva, osećanja i pitanja onog drugog učesnika. Svi oni zajedno izdvajaju pitanja odgov- ornosti, sigurnosti i potrebu za preduzimanjem krajnje poštenih i suštinskih radnji“. Pri tome, mora postojati najmanje pet el- emenata koji jednom procesu daju atribut „re- storativan“. Restorativna pravda zahteva potpuno učešće i saglasnost svih onih koji su na bilo koji način bili pogođeni izvršenjem krivičnog dela – žrtve , delinkventa, njihovih porodica i prijatelja, kao i osoba iz društvene zajednice. Zatim, restorativna pravda pokušava da isceli ono što je uništeno. Zato 2 Aktivnosti restorativne pravde, mnogo češće primenjivane u SAD, određuju se kao: uticaj iskaza žrtvi, klasifi kacija i panel diskusija, medijacija (posredovanje) između žrtve i učinioca, društveni servis, restitucija i društveni restorativni odbori. O restorativnoj pravdi videti literaturu na adresi: http://www.restorativejustice.com/published.html Dr Miomira KOSTIĆ Temida 7 se proces usmerava na potrebe žrtve (šta je potreb- no učiniti da se trauma zaceli; povraćaj osećanja sigurnosti), delinkventa (šta je potrebno uraditi da se zlo više nikada ne ponovi; šta preduzeti da se delinkvent ponaša u saglasnosti sa postignutim do- govorom) i članova zajednice (šta će im omogućiti da se osećaju sigurno; koje korake treba preduzeti za unapređenje zajednice tako da ima manje izgle- da da se zločin dogodi u budućnosti). Sledeće što je neophodno je da postoji pot- puna i neposredna odgovornost svih učesnika. Optužene osobe suočavaju se sa svojim žrtvama i drugima koji trpe posledice zločina i kojima je data mogućnost da objasne svoje ponašanje, preuzmu punu odgovornost i budu deo procesa koji odlučuje o načinu kako da objedini potrebe svih zainteresovanih. Takođe, restorativna pravda teži da vrati u ce- linu sve ono što je bilo „razdvojeno”, uništeno krivičnim delom. Naime, zločin deli članove jedne društvene zajednice na „mi-oni” način razmišljanja. Restorativne rasprave nalaze načina da prevaziđu tu razliku, tako da „mi i oni” budu ponovo povezani unutar jedne društvene zajednice postavljene na zdravim osnovama. Povraćaj u jednu celinu svih članova zajednice onemogućava izolaciju unutar zajednice. Izolacija se inače javlja kao prirodan pratilac zločina. To je otuđenost koju osećaju kako delinkvent i žrtva , tako i ostali članovi društvene zajednice koji trpe posledice. Međutim, restorativ- na rasprava ne može da poveže žrtvu i delinkven- ta u nešto što je već postojalo kao nezdrav, zlostavljajući odnos. Na kraju, rasprava o restor- ativnoj pravdi stremi ka tome da osnaži zajednicu u cilju da se spreči dalje povređivanje time „što će izgraditi odnose i obratiti pažnju na značajna socijalna pitanja koja su na prvom mestu uzroci zločina“ (Coward, 2000: 7). 3 3 U literaturi se navodi i to da je restorativna pravda „način razmišljanja, način ponašanja i način rasuđivanja”. Ovakvo određenje izložio je Bria Huculak, sudija iz Kanade, koji je učestvovao na PATHS konferenciji o restorativnoj pravdi 1995. Inače, tokom devedesetih godina prošloga veka neki pisci su opisali restorativnu pravdu kao odgovor na kriminalno ponašanje koje zahteva da budu nadoknađeni gubici kao posledice zločina od kojih su patile žrtve , da se olakša uspostavljanje mira i ostvare miroljubivi odnosi između suprotnih strana. Tokom 1991. u Kanadi restorativna pravda je opisivana kao postojanje principa koji podržavaju i obeštećuju žrtvu uz posredovanje , obeštećuju društvenu zajednicu i uz pomoć kojih se učestvuje u rehabilitaciji delinkvenata uz ograničenu upotrebu restrikcija i nadzora. Uvođenje i primena restorativne pravde Zagovornici restorativne pravde zalažu se za neograničenu ekspanziju u njenoj primeni, dok kritizeri ističu da preterani ciljevi samo podrivaju ostvarenje skromnijih ali realnijih uspeha. Neke od glavnih kritika usmerene su na to da se primenom restorativne pravde ne ostvaruju proporcionalni rezultati. Međutim, proporcionalnost i nije jedna od ključnih vrednosti restorativne pravde, kao ni evaluacija njenih uspeha, zato što ona zastupa zadovoljenje svih učesnika tog postupka, što nije suštinska vrednost niti cilj konvencionalnog krivičnopravnog sistema. Smatra se da je osećanje stida važniji vid kontrole kriminaliteta od izrečene krivične sankcije. Kako osećanje stida ne bi proiz- velo nepovoljne posledice po delinkventa i žrtvu potrebno je da se proces okonča ritualnim činom kroz ceremoniju reintegracije (Braithwaite, Daly, 2001: 29). Neke ženske feminističke grupe se ne saglaša- vaju sa primenom procesa restorativne pravde u slučajevima porodičnog nasilja. Naime, u drugoj polovini dvadesetog veka feministkinje su seksu- alno nasilje i nasilje u porodici proglasile pojavama koje zaslužuju da budu tretirane kao zločini koje treba kazniti. Restorativna pravda, sa svoje strane, omogućava da napredak postignut na tom planu bude umanjen zato što dozvoljava da se o takvim zločinima raspravlja na privatnim sastancima, gde žene mogu biti dodatno viktimizirane zbog nemogućnosti da se izbegne neravnoteža moći. S druge strane, u Kanadi Council on Justice and Corrections je u toku 1996. godine podneo izveštaj zasnovan na istraživanju iskustava žrtava nasilja i utvrdio da je ...“kontakt između žrtve i krivičnog suda bio primarni izvor reviktimizacije, frustracije, razočaranja, dosađivanja, pre nego li doprinos u rešavanju problema žrtava“. Isto tako, nevladina organizacija iz New Foundlend-a Provincial Asso- ciation Against Family Violence PAAFV iznela je re- zultate sopstvenog istraživanja o položaju žrtava u krivičnom postupku. Prema ovom izveštaju „žrtve su zabrinute oko sopstvenog minimalnog učešća u krivičnom postupku i da se nekada osećaju kao os- obe kojima se sudi umesto osobe koja je optužena za zločin..., a sadašnji sistem funkcioniše tako što delinkvente radije zadržava u sistemu nego što ih ohrabruje da prestanu da vrše zločin“ (Coward, 2000: 2). 8 Jedan od glavnih pobornika restorativne pravde u SAD Tomas Cavanagh smatra da je klasičan krivičnopravni sistem doživeo krah i da stvara “spi- ralu učešća siromašnih, mentalno bolesnih i mar- ginalaca”, a da restorativna pravda pomaže da ljudi “žive život sa strašću, ispunjen ličnim i zajedničkim ciljevima i snovima u težnji da dostignu svoje pot- pune mogućnosti”. Ovaj bivši novinar koji je proveo dvadeset i osam godina kao izveštač iz suda, sma- tra restorativnu pravdu izazovom koji je “posvećen kritičkom razmišljanju i doživotnom učenju u toku kojeg se postavljaju pitanja na koja se nema uvek odgovor, gde se čovek usuđuje na nešto izvanred- no i preuzima rizik” (Cavanagh, 1998:24). Identifi kacija procesa restorativne pravde i vrste „putokaza“ Howard Zehr i Harry Mika predložili su izves- tan broj „putokaza“ u cilju lakše identifi kacije procesa restorativne pravde. Učesnici procesa se radije usredsređuju na pretrpljenu štetu nego na kršenje zakona. Prema žrtvi i prema učiniocu se iskazuje uravnotežena briga i obe se strane uključuju u krivični postupak. Popravljanje po- sledica koje je žrtva pretrpela vrši se kroz povećan interes za zadovoljenje potreba žrtve. Delinkvent se podržava i simultano ohrabruje da razume, pri- hvati i izrazi spremnost da ispravi zlo koje je naneo. U procesu restorativne pravde mora se prepoznati potreba delinkventa da ispuni obaveze koje su ostvarive, a ne predstavljaju kažnjavanje. Mora se razviti mogućnost da između žrtve i učinioca bude uspostavljen neposredan ili posredan dijalog. S druge strane, ovi zagovornici restorativne pravde ne isključuju značaj krivičnog sudskog postupka i smatraju da sama društvena zajedni- ca, ili preciznije uža socijalna sredina u čijem se miljeu odigrao zločin, treba da bude deo sudskog postupka, pogotovu kroz povećanje njenih kapa- citeta da prepozna zločin i odgovori na njega. U procesu „lečenja“ društva od delinkvencije radije treba podsticati saradnju i reintegraciju nego se- paraciju i korekciju. S obzirom da u procesu resto- rativne pravde učestvuju po svojim obeležjima he- terogene grupe ljudi, posebno se moraju opažati izvesni neočekivani postupci i neočekivani do- bijeni rezultati. Kao poslednji u nizu „putokaza“ je onaj kojim se iskazuje poštovanje za dostojanstvo svakoga, posebno žrtava, delinkvenata i svih dru- gih učesnika u procesu ostvarivanja pravde (McE- voy, Mika, Hudson, 2002: 469). Provincial Association Against Family Violence PAAFV zastupa fi losofski pristup koncepta restor- ativne pravde. To nije samo model postupanja drugačiji od tradicionalnog krivičnopravnog siste- ma, već fi losofi ja ili vizija koja u svesti odražava potrebe žrtve, delinkventa i društvene zajednice. Ova asocijacija se poziva na „...merodavne sudove pravednosti u zajednici i suđenja u krugu kao pod- sticaje ili inicijative u procesu restorativne pravde i identifi kuje neke oblike rešavanja konfl ikata kroz alternativno raspravljanje kao prirodne restor- ativne procese“. Po drugima, restorativna pravda usmerena je na izazivanje osećanja sramote i oproštaj, pa je to postupanje isključivo za dobrobit žrtve, a ne delinkventa (Coward, 2000: 6). Vrednosti kojima teži restorativna pravda Restorativna pravda se zasniva na uravnoteženom usmeravanju na delinkventa, žrtvu i zajednicu. Vrednosni sudovi usmereni na delinkventa obuhvataju izvinjenje i osećanje stida za učinjeno delo i reintegraciju. U odnosu na žrtvu, razmatra se pričinjena šteta i mogućnost davanja oproštaja delinkventu, dok bi za društvenu zajed- nicu bilo važno da se uspostave pređašnji odnosi. Rezultati i mere programa restorativne pravde zasnivaju se na osnovnim vrednostima koje se od- nose na sva tri učesnika ovog procesa. Delinkvent treba da uputi pisano ili usmeno izvinjenje žrtvi i socijalnoj grupi koje trpe zbog njegovog postupka. On mora naučiti da prepozna sopstvenu odgovor- nost bez posmatranja sebe kao žrtve okolnosti kao i da stekne saznanja o zlu koje je naneo žrtvi. Rein- tegracija delinkventa znači učenje kako da se vrati u društvenu zajednicu, posebno kroz plan postu- panja u cilju „lečenja“ nastalog štetnog postupka. Kod žrtve treba identifi kovati i proceniti nane- senu štetu. U svakom pojedinačnom slučaju pravi se plan popravljanja štete. Žrtva treba da prihvati izvinjenje od delinkventa i da iskaže oproštaj. Vred- nosti vezane za društvenu zajednicu usmerene su na popravljanje uništenih odnosa i uspostavljanje novih odnosa unutar zajednice. Retributivna pravda teži stvaranju sigurnosti u društvu za razliku od restorativne pravde koja ima za cilj uspostavljanje mira u zajednici. Retributivna Dr Miomira KOSTIĆ Temida 9 pravda usmerena je na izdvajanje nepoželjnih lju- di, kakvi su kriminalci, time što će im se izreći ka- zna zatvora, kao najrasprostranjenija vrsta krivične sankcije po obimu izricanja u pravnosnažnim osuđujućim presudama. Otuda i mišljenje većine zastupnika restorativne pravde da proces retribu- cije nije dao željene rezultate zato što su njime ug- lavnom obuhvaćeni oni „drugačiji“, ljudi sa margina života, koji najčešće i dospevaju pred krivični sud.4 To su najčešće: beskućnici, mentalno hendikepira- ni, siromašni građani i pripadnici manjina. Stvaran- je mira u zajednici podrazumeva postupanje sa delinkventima koji su deo društvene zajednice jer će se oni vratiti natrag u tu zajednicu i posle izdržane kazne zatvora. Društvena zajednica, koja se neposredno odnosi na svakog pojedinačnog delinkventa obuhvata: porodicu, prijatelje i osobe sa kojima je delinkvent u poslovnim odnosima. Ovi odnosi obezbeđuju okruženje za razvitak osećanja za društvenu savest, svest da nečiji postupci pogađaju druge ljude i želju da se osoba ostvari kao uzoran član društva. Uspostavljanje standarda za restor- ativnu pravdu U literaturi o restorativnoj pravdi uspostavljan- je standarda vezanih za sprovođenje ovog procesa posmatra se kao utemeljenje izvesnih fi losofskih koncepcija. Naime, smatra se da je neophodno u nekom obliku postaviti minimum odgovornosti i minimum broja standarda koji će se nadmetati za primat u primeni. Takođe, ljudska prava su ta koja moraju biti zaštićena procesima restorativne pravde. Mnogi učesnici procesa restorativne pravde sebe identifi kuju kao osobe angažovane u borbi protiv opresivne državne strukture, koja je posebno vidljiva u penitencijarnoj praksi mod- ernih država. Za većinu zastupnika restorativne pravde ovaj koncept je fi losofski, metodološki i politički značajan. Restorativni metod znači postupak kroz koji se razmatra značaj posledica nepravde nane- sene građanima, tako da sve one budu pojedinačno priznate kao početna tačka u njihovom lečenju i sprečavanju, kao i promenu uslova koji su doveli do razvijanja nepravde. Građani se ohrabruju da 4 Videti mišljenja Cavanagh-a, Braithwait-a i drugih autora na sajtu: http://www.restorativejustice.com/published. html preuzmu odgovornost za događaje koji su posled- njih nekoliko vekova posmatrani isključivo kao predmet interesovanja države (Konstantinović- Vilić, Kostić, 2006: 106). Osnovni standard je da restorativni proces treba da teži izbegavanju dominacije. Ipak, domi- nacija je i dalje zastupljena u restorativnom pro- cesu kao što se može uočiti i u bilo kojoj drugoj sferi društvene interakcije. Zato svaki program koji u sebi sadrži atribut „restorativan“ mora ujed- no biti angažovan u prevenciji dominacije. Svaki učesnik konferencije koji ne dozvoljava drugome da iznese svoj stav ili teži da dominira nad dru- gim učesnicima mora biti sprečen u takvom svom nastojanju (Braithwaite, 2002: 565). Ukoliko domi- nacija ipak opstaje ili se drugi učesnici boje da joj se neposredno suprotstave onda moderator treba da zahteva da govore oni nad kojima se vrši sub- ordinacija. Neravnoteža moći predstavlja strukturalni fenomen. Struktura restorativnih procesa mora bi- ti takva da minimalizuje neravnotežu moći.5 Usvo- jeni standardi usmeravaju pripremni rad učesnika postupka upravo ka postizanju ravnoteže između učesnika postupka. Organizovane grupe za- stupnika interesa pojedinih žrtava imaju posebno značajnu ulogu kada postoji neravnoteža moći iskazana u samom deliktu. Time su obuhvaćene grupe za podršku ženama i deci kada je porodično nasilje predmet debate i grupe za podršku ekološke sredine kada se vrše krivična dela protiv prirodne sredine od strane moćnih korporacija. Smatra se da je podesan postupak najvažniji domen gde se javila potreba za defi nisanjem standarda. Delinkvent treba da ima pravo na sa- vet advokata o tome da li da prihvati da učestvuje u postupku ili ne. Međutim, suština procesa re- storativne pravde, prema Braithwaitu, je da se prevaziđe „suparnički legalizam“, tako da učesnici budu ohrabreni da govore svojim sopstvenim 5 Postupak restorativne pravde koji se sprovodi prema maloletnom delinkventu, na primer, ne sme se odvijati tako da on bude optuživan u „sobi prepunoj odraslih ljudi“ (Haines, 1998). Ovom postupku treba da prisustvuju odrasle osobe koje sebe vide kao odgovorne da zastupaju interese maloletnika. Ukoliko se takve osobe ne pronađu za prvi krug, postupak se prekida i vraća se u pređašnje stanje da bi se ponovo potražile one osobe koje će zastupati interese deteta i podržati dete. Slično je i u postupanju prema učiniocima porodičnog nasilja koje bi zastupali njihovi patrijarhalni branioci (Citirano prema: Braithwaite, 2002: 565). 10 rečima radije nego da za njih govore „legalni mirot- vorci koji mogu imati interes da polarizuju kon- fl ikt“ (Braithwaite, 2002: 565). S obzirom da proces restorativne pravde teži da reintegriše štetu i suz- bije stigmatizaciju važno je zabraniti bilo koji oblik degradacije ili ponižavanja u tretmanu. 6 Ključni princip procesa je poklanjanje iste pažnje svim učesnicima postupka – delinkventu, žrtvi i društvenoj zajednici. Moguće je da položaj poje- dinih žrtava bude iskorišćen kao potpora u pro- gramima koji su orijentisani samo na prava žrtava. Takvi programi su moralno neprihvatljivi. Pažljivo slušanje izlaganja svih učesnika u postupku pred- stavlja zabranu nepoštovanja ili ponižavanja dru- gih i sprečavanje degradirajućih načina reakcije ili kažnjavanja. Pravo na žalbu je jedan od osnovnih standarda koji mora biti ispoštovan. U onim situacijama kada je krivično pravo osnov po kome se izriče sank- cija, u postupku restorativne pravde delinkventi moraju imati pravo žalbe protiv izrečene sankcije državnom organu, odnosno nadležnom krivičnom sudu. Međutim, to ne znači da svi mehanizmi krivičnopravne procedure istovremeno odgov- araju ideji postupka restorativne pravde. To se posebno odnosi na prisustvo javnosti u postupku. S jedne strane, izbegavanje stigmatizacije poje- dinih učesnika u postupku restorativne pravde i obezbeđivanje dijaloga bez dominacije podra- zumeva izvesnu diskretnost, pogotovu onda kada učesnici nisu saglasni da se postupak odvija uz prisustvo stručne ili opšte javnosti. Ako su učesnici saglasni da se postupak odvija uz prisustvo javnos- ti važno je obezbediti učešće istraživača, kritičara, novinara, sudija i kolega iz programa restorativne pravde drugih sredina. Tako će se izneti kritički stavovi, iskustva drugih postupaka, kao i načinjene pogreške. U literaturi se iznose mišljenja koja idu u prilog ovom drugom shvatanju i ističe važnost novinskih izveštača čiji je zadatak da objektivno 6 Postoji standard po kome delinkventi i žrtve imaju pravo na prisustvo advokata za vreme sprovođenja procesa restorativne pravde. Međutim, standard po kome advokati imaju pravo da govore u postupku čini se ipak neopravdanim jer se takav govornik smatra pretnjom ka „integritetu osnaživanja procesa restorativne pravde“. To ne znači da advokat treba da ima bezuslovnu zabranu govora. Naprotiv, ako se svi učesnici saglase da treba da čuju neko stručno mišljenje onda to mišljenje treba i izneti tokom postupka. To posebno važi u slučaju kada su pravnici potpisali legalni sporazum o saradnji i prošli obuku za posredovanje. Ibid. obaveštavaju o poštovanju ili nepoštovanju os- novnih standarda restorativne pravde. U formulisanju standarda restorativne pravde moraju se ispoštovati i neki međunarodno prizna- ti instrumenti o zaštiti osnovnih ljudskih prava. Opšta deklaracija o pravima čoveka UN defi niše specifi čne vrednosti i prava ljudi koji se promovišu i kroz proces restorativne pravde.7 Deklaracija obuh- vata pravo na život, slobodu i bezbednost ličnosti, pravo na zaštitu od samovoljnog oduzimanja tuđe imovine, pravo na zdravlje i medicinsku brigu, kao i pravo na učešće u demokratskim procesima. Sa stanovišta restorativne pravde interesantan je čl. 5 koji predviđa da niko neće biti izložen torturi ili surovom, nehumanom i ponižavajućem postupku ili kazni. Zagovornici restorativne pravde smatraju da su države članice UN interpretirale ovaj član na najpermisivniji način koji ne zadovoljava standarde restorativne pravde. Zato je ovaj član za njih neka vrsta „izazova“ za primenu u restorativnoj pravdi, kao minimum „anti-kažnjivog prostora“. Međunarodni pakt o građanskim i političkim pravima iz 1966. godine usmeren je ka daljem „samoodređivanju“ građana država članica.8 Naime, Paktom je propisano da svako lice koje je uhapšeno ili pritvoreno zbog krivičnog dela bude u najkraćem roku predato sudiji ili nekoj drugoj vlasti zakonom ovlašćenoj da vrši sudske funk- cije i mora u razumnom roku da bude suđeno ili oslobođeno (čl. 6). Takođe Paktom je predviđeno da su svi jednaki pred sudovima i sudovima pravde (čl. 14). U Međunarodnom paktu o ekonomskim, socijalnim i kulturnim pravima države članice se obavezuju da priznaju pravo koje ima svako lice na najbolje psihičko i mentalno zdravlje koje može da postigne (čl. 12).9 Godine 1989. usvojen je Drugi opcioni protokol Pakta o građanskim i političkim pravima koji obuhvata učešće političkih partija u aboliciji smrtne kazne. Takođe, zagovornici restor- ativne pravde saglasni su sa svim vrednostima i pravima iz Konvencije o eliminaciji svih oblika dis- kriminacije prema ženama10 i Standardnim mini- 7 Opšta deklaracija o pravima čoveka, usvojena i proklamovana od strane Generalne Skupštine rezolucijom 217A (III) od 10. decembra 1948. godine. 8 Zakon o ratifi kaciji Međunarodnog pakta o građanskim i političkim pravima , Službeni list SFRJ br. 7/71. 9 Zakon o ratifi kaciji Međunarodnog pakta o ekonomskim, socijalnim i kulturnim pravima, Sl. List SFRJ br. 7/71. 10 Sukcesorskom izjavom od 12. marta 2001. godine, Dr Miomira KOSTIĆ Temida 11 malnim pravilima za mere nepritvaranja iz 1990. godine (Tokijska pravila). Za izgradnju i primenu re- storativne pravde važne su odredbe Deklaracije o osnovnim principima pravde za žrtve zločina i zlou- potrebe moći koju je usvojila Generalna skupština UN-a 1985. godine. Ona obuhvata relevantne vred- nosti koje bliže objašnjavaju instrumente zaštite osnovnih ljudskih prava poput: „zaštite okoline“ (čl. 10), „sažaljenja“ (čl. 4), „povraćaja u pređašnje stanje“, „obeštećenja“ (čl. 5), „restauraciju prava“ (čl. 8) i reguliše „normalne mehanizme za razrešavanje sporova, uključujući medijaciju, presuđivanje i uobičajenu pravdu i lokalne običaje“ (čl. 7), što je pravni osnov za primenu restorativne pravde u svim onim situacijama kada treba olakšati po- mirenje i obeštetiti žrtvu. Osim toga na evrop- skom planu značajna je i Evropska konvencija za zaštitu ljudskih prava i osnovnih sloboda iz 1950. godine11. (Papić, 2002: 396) Prema odredbama Konvencije niko ne sme biti podvrgnut mučenju ili nečovečnom ili ponižavajućem postupanju ili kažnjavanju (čl. 3). Svako ima prava na pravičnu i javnu raspravu u razumnom roku pred nezavisnim i nepristrasnim sudom, obrazovanim na osnovu zakona (čl. 6). Konvencijom je zabranjena diskrim- inacija po bilo kom osnovu, kao što su: pol, rasa, boja kože, jezik, veroispovest, političko ili drugo mišljenje, nacionalno ili socijalno poreklo, veza sa nekom nacionalnom manjinom i drugo (čl. 14). Na evropskom kontinentu, sadašnji oblik medi- jacije između žrtve i učinioca otpočeo je da se primenjuje osamdesetih godina prošloga veka. Prvi pilot projekat sproveden je 1981. godine u Norveškoj, a Finska je sledila taj put dve godine kasnije. U Austriji model je nazvan „rešavanje delikta izvan suda“ i prvi put je predstavljen od strane države pred maloletničkim sudovima 1988. godine, a zatim je ugrađen u Zakonik o krivičnom Srbija i Crna Gora je nastavila članstvo i u svim drugim konvencijama koje se odnose na prava žena, a kojima je depozitar Generalni sekretar UN. Srbija i Crna Gora je država članica Konvencije o eliminaciji svih oblika diskriminacije prema ženama. Opcioni protokol uz ovu Konvenciju ratifi kovan je decembra 2002. godine. Inicijalni izveštaj o primeni Međunarodnog pakta o građanskim i političkim pravima u SRJ za period od 1992-2002. godine, 2003 Ministarstvo za ljudska i manjinska prava Srbije i Crne Gore, Beograd 11 Evropska konvencija za zaštitu ljudskih prava i osnovnih sloboda, izmenjena u skladu sa Protokolom br. 11, Rim, 4. novembra 1950. postupku od 1. januara 2000. godine. U Engles- koj, posle skromnih eksperimenata iz 1979. go- dine, u periodu od 1985-87. godine primenjena su četiri projekta, ali nisu naišli na takav odjek kao u Nemačkoj. Naime, u Nemačkoj je taj proces počeo skoro u isto vreme kada i u Engleskoj, ali se do sada razvilo preko četiri stotine službi za primenu restorativne pravde. Uopšte, tokom devedesetih godina prošlog veka, ovaj se proces proširio u Evropi. 8. decem- bra 2000. godine, posle dvogodišnjih priprema, ustanovljen je Evropski forum za medijaciju između žrtve i učinioca i restorativnu pravdu (European Forum for Victim-Off ender Mediation and Restor- ative Justice), sada samo Evropski forum za restor- ativnu pravdu (European Forum for Restorative Justice). Tada je donet Statut ove organizacije, gde je u čl. 4 određen opšti cilj rada Foruma. Taj cilj sas- toji se u tome da forum pruži pomoć u ustanovlja- vanju i razvoju medijacije između učinioca i žrtve i u drugim oblicima prakse za primenu restorativne pravde širom Evrope.12 Evropska unija usvojila je dokument pod na- zivom Okvirna odluka o položaju žrtve u krivičnim postupcima (the Framework Decision on the stand- ing of victims in criminal proceedings) 22. marta 2002. godine. Pun opseg zaštite zagarantovan Od- lukom počeo je da se primenjuje tek posle četiri go- dine. Mere u cilju umanjenja teškoća oko primene Odluke u lokalnim zajednicama i obezbeđivanje pristupa besplatnoj pravnoj pomoći stupile su na snagu tek marta 2004., dok je promocija medijaci- je bila predviđena za 2006. godinu.13 Neki autori, poput Braithwait-a, daju predloge standarda koji bi bili osnov za postupanje. (Bra- ithwait, 2002:569) Tako, ovaj autor razlikuje stan- darde ograničenja ili prinude koji precizno od- ređuju prava i ograničenja i standarde uvećavanja ili maksimizirajuće standarde. Standardi ogra- ničenja, po predlogu ovog autora, bili bi: odsustvo dominacije; ostvarivanje prava; poštovanje gornjih zakonskih maksimuma krivičnih sankcija; slušanje drugih uz puno poštovanje; poklanjanje podjed- nake pažnje svim učesnicima; odgovornost i mo- gućnost žalbe; poštovanje svih osnovnih ljudskih 12 Videti: www. euforum.org (pristup sajtu 15.3.2007.) 13 Videti: New rights for victims of crime in Europe - The future.htm (pristup sajtu 17.3.2007.) 12 prava proklamovanih dokumentima UN. Standar- di najvećih vrednosti ili maksimizirajući standardi odnose se na: uspostavljanje ljudskog dostojan- stva; obnavljanje uništene imovine; obnavljanje narušenog zdravlja; obnavljanje uništenih ljudskih odnosa; obnavljanje zajednice; obnavljanje okoli- ne; emocionalno obnavljanje; obnavljanje slobo- de; obnavljanje sažaljenja i brige za druge; uspo- stavljanje mira; obnavljanje građanskog osećanja dužnosti; priprema društvene podrške za neogra- ničeni razvoj ljudskih sposobnosti; prevencija bu- duće nepravde. Ove vrednosti ne proističu samo iz tekstova međunarodnih dokumenata o ljudskim pravima, već predstavljaju i deo empirijskog iskustva saku- pljenog kroz iskaze žrtava i delinkvenata o tome šta bi oni želeli da se postigne kroz proces restor- ativne pravde. U standardima ograničenja pored zabrane dominacije važno mesto zauzima i standard os- tvarivanja prava. Ostvarivanje prava znači da svi učesnici treba da imaju mogućnost da budu „opunomoćeni“ da iskažu svoje sopstvene priče na sebi svojstveni način. Time bi obznanili bilo koji osećaj nepravde koji žele da vide kao ispravljen. Nepoštovanjem standarda najvećih vrednosti bi se, zbog subjektivnog doživljaja nepravde, postigla netrpeljivost. Prihvatanjem standarda ograničenja učesnici nisu limitirani u postizanju standarda sa liste najvećih vrednosti. Kod standarda najvećih vrednosti mera se ne sastoji u tome da oni uvek budu svi striktno sprovedeni, već da se razvijaju kroz veliki broj slučajeva koji su u programu restor- ativne pravde. Evaluacioni proces sastojao bi se u njihovom poređenju sa slučajevima koji nisu bili u programu. Sve ove vrednosti su restriktivne u određivanju kazni. Njihovo poštovanje i sprovođenje teži ka primeni nekih drugih mera zato što ciljevi i sredst- va sprovođenja restorativne i retributivne pravde nisu isti. Standardi najvećih vrednosti predstavljaju različite oblike lečenja koji imaju svoje uporište u međunarodno priznatim ljudskim pravima i empirijskom iskustvu onoga što učesnici žele da „izleče“ kroz proces restorativne pravde. Emocio- nalno obnavljanje ili emocionalna restoracija tako će za nekoga biti oslobađanje od osećanja straha, za drugog učesnika oslobađanje od mržnje, za nekog sledećeg od stida ili nepoželjnih osobina sopstvenog karaktera. Obezbeđivanje socijalne podrške za potpuni razvoj ljudskih sposobnosti usmeren je ka organima formalne društvene kon- trole i njihovom daljem opstanku kao razvojnih a ne statičnih institucija. Smatra se, naime, da državne, regulativne institucije onemogućavaju razvoj ljudskih sposobnosti, među kojima organi krivičnopravnog sistema usmereni na kažnjavanje predstavljaju najtipičniji primer. U procesu sprovođenja restorativne pravde Braithwaite ističe značaj pomoćnih standarda koje posmatra kao: žaljenje ili pokajanje zbog učinjene nepravde; izvinjenje, osuda čina, oproštaj, milost. (Braithwaite, 2002: 570) Svi ovi standardi su ugrađeni u međunarodno- pravne dokumente o ljudskim pravima. Lista ovih standarda razlikuje se od liste standarda uvećavanja po konceptualnom kriterijumu. Desmond Tutu (1999) je izjavio da budućnost ne postoji bez oproštaja, što je postala ideja vodilja mnogih po- bornika restorativne pravde. Međutim, oproštaj se razlikuje od slušanja drugih uz puno poštovanje, što mora biti osnovni standard restorativne pravde. Zalaganje da svako bude saslušan ne znači istovre- meno insistirati na oproštaju, požurivati davanje oprosta. Braithwaite14 čak insistira na tome da je okrutno i pogrešno očekivati od žrtve zločina da oprosti (Braithwaite, 2002: 571). Slično tome, pokajanje koje je silom ili formalno izvučeno iz delinkventa takođe nema moralnu snagu.15 Zaključak Restorativna pravda, umesto retribuciji teži ka ponovnom uspostavljanju stanja narušenog izvršenjem krivičnog dela, što se postiže primenom raznih metoda: posredovanjem između učinioca krivičnog dela i žrtve , izvinjenjem, mirenjem, na- knadom štete ili drugim oblicima nadoknade pričinjene štete žrtvi. 14 Dalje ovaj autor konstatuje da su izvinjenje, oproštaj i milosrđe darovi koji „imaju značenje samo onda ako izviru u iskrenoj želji osobe koja oprašta, izvinjava se ili prima milosrđe“. 15 Upoređujući predložene standarde Braithwait ističe da se standardi ograničavanja moraju prihvatiti i primeniti kao ograničenja. Listu standarda najvećih vrednosti zagovornici restorativne pravde treba „aktivno da ohrabruju“ u restorativnom procesu, dok pomoćne standarde posmatra kao nešto što ne treba da se „požuruje“ u restorativnom procesu, već oni predstavljaju rezervne ali i sastavne delove uspešnog procesa restorativne pravde. Dr Miomira KOSTIĆ Temida 13 Teškoće u sprovođenju ovih standarda su u tome što ih neki posmatraju kao neodređene vred- nosti i manjkave specifi čnosti za sprovođenje pro- cesa restorativne pravde. Međutim, oni treba da se primenjuju u praksi tako što će evaluacija na osn- ovu prethodnih empirijskih pokazatelja iz primene pomoći da se podstakne savetodavna regulativa za razliku od legalističke regulative u postupku sprovođenja retributivne pravde. U literaturi se kao primer navodi pravo na brzo suđenje koje je predviđeno odredbama zakonika o krivičnom po- stupku savremenih država16. Ovo pravo predstav- ljeno je i kao specifi čna odredba iz Pekinških pravila za maloletničko pravosuđe.17 Međutim, upravo ovo pravilo može biti preispitano sa stanovišta fi losof- skog koncepta restorativne pravde. Naime, praksa je pokazala da u slučajevima kada su žrtve teško traumatizovane izvršenim krivičnim delom potreb- no je da protekne određeni vremenski period pre nego one postanu spremne da prihvate „lečenje“ kroz postupak restorativne pravde. Žrtvama treba omogućiti to pravo ali ne u onoj meri da posluži kao izgovor za proizvoljno zadržavanje delinkven- ta u pritvoru koji još nije oglašen krivim. S druge strane, neka prava, kao pravo na žalbu preuzeto iz legalističke regulative je visoko specifi čan standard u sprovođenju restorativne pravde koji, bez izuzet- ka, mora biti ispoštovan. U domaćoj stručnoj i opštoj javnosti pozna- vanje standarda i principa restorativne pravde nije zastupljeno u većoj meri. Kancelarija UNICEF- a u Beogradu organizovala je nekolicinu stručnih skupova sa centrima za socijalni rad, timovima za suzbijanje maloletničke delinkvencije pri sek- retarijatima unutrašnjih poslova i ustanovama za izvršenje vaspitnih mera institucionalnog karak- tera. Međutim, smatra se da sve to nije bilo dovolj- no za bolje upoznavanje ovog procesa. Savremene države teže da kao osnov komuni- kacije među ljudima razviju toleranciju – trpelji- vost prema različitostima, bez obzira da li su one etičke, rasne ili ekonomske prirode. Na različitost 16 Ovo pravo predviđeno je i u čl. 16. Zakonika o krivičnom postupku SRJ po kome okrivljeni ima pravo da u najkraćem roku bude izveden pred sud i da mu bude suđeno bez odlaganja. Sud je dužan da postupak sprovede bez odlaganja i da onemogući svaku zloupotrebu prava koja pripada licima koja učestvuju u postupku. 17 Videti: United Nations Standard Minimum Rules for the Administration of Juvenile Justice – Beijing Rules (1995) Defence for Children International, s. 5. treba gledati bez prigovaranja. Međutim, trpelji- vost često nije dovoljna da se njome najtačnije odredi sadašnjost i po mišljenju nekih pobornika restorativne pravde, ona nije rešenje. Tolerancija, sama po sebi, kao pojedinačni, izdvojeni person- alni akt, ne utiče na „lečenje“ društvenih rana niti pak eliminiše socijalnu izolaciju i očaj (Cavanagh, 2000). Zagovornici restorativne pravde radije ističu da rešavanje pitanja društvenih devijacija pre treba da se zasniva na „opštoj dobrobiti“ za- jednice. Opšta dobrobit zajednice određuje se kao „čitava mreža društvenih uslova koji omogućavaju pojedincima i grupama ljudi da se u potpunosti razviju i žive punim životom ali tako da svako ne bude usmeren samo na sebe, već su svi odgovorni za sve druge oko sebe“ (Cavanagh, 2000). Opšta dobrobit u jednoj ljudskoj zajednici znači da svako ima obavezu da doprinese razvoju opšteg dobra u društvu, u interesu pravde, kao i u iznalaženju rešenja socijalnih pitanja u jednoj društvenoj zajednici. Upravo se na tome zasniva osnovna kritika retributivne pravde. Naime, re- tributivni krivičnopravni sistem upravljen je na kažnjavanje delinkvenata, naročito putem izri- canja kazni institucionalnog karaktera. Ustanove za izvršenje kazne zatvora često se opisuju rečima “uvreda ljudskog dostojanstva ...i otrov u krvotoku nacije“. Takav sistem nije uticao na suzbijanje krim- inaliteta zato što se ne bavi razrešenjem uzroka kriminalnog ponašanja. Ti uzroci najčešće se nala- ze u najbližem socijalnom okruženju delinkventa, u sredini u koju se on inače vraća po isteku kazne. Vizija restorativne pravde, u kontekstu opšteg dobra, usmerena je na postizanje mira u društvenoj zajednici putem popravljanja odnosa u društvu, što se odnosi na sve članove zajednice. Suština sprovođenja restorativne pravde je „lečenje“ sva- ke osobe koja je povezana sa zločinom putem popravljanja, a ne putem kažnjavanja. Celokupan proces treba da se zasniva na izvinjenju, oproštaju i uspostavljanju čvrste povezanosti ljudi unutar za- jednice. Literatura Braithwaite, J., Daly, K. (2001) Muškosti, nasilje i kontrola za- jednice, Temida, 2, str. 29-44. Braithwaite, J. (2002) Setting Standards for Restorative Justice, British Journal of Criminology 42, str. 563-577. 14 Cavanagh, T. (1998) Adopting New Values for the Courts: What is Restorative Justice? The Court Manager, 13/ 2/3, Williams- burg, VA: National Association for Court Management, str. 24- 27. http://www.restorativejustice.com/Tom.html Cavanagh T. (2000) Restorative Justice and the Common Good: Creating a Culture of Forgiveness and Reconciliation, BLUEPRINT for Social Justice, Vo. LIII, No. 8, str. 24-27, http:// www.lojno.edu/twomey/blueprint/blueprint/april2000.htm. Coward, S. (2000) Restorative Justice in Cases of Domestic Vio- lence: Healing Justice? Directed Interdisciplinary Studies, Car- leton University. http://www.hotpeachpages.com/resources/ rs_cases_of_dv_sv.htm od 17.02.2004. Inicijalni izveštaj o primeni Međunarodnog pakta o građanskim i političkim pravima u SRJ za period od 1992-2002. godine, 2003, Ministarstvo za ljudska i manjinska prava Srbije i Crne Gore, Beograd. Konstantinović-Vilić, S., Kostić, M. (2006) Penologija. Niš: SVEN. Kostić, M. (2005) Restorativna pravda – smisao i mogućnosti primene, Socijalna misao, 2-3, str. 45-66. McEvoy, K., Mika, H., Hudson, B. (2002) „Introduction – Prac- tice, Reformance and Prospects for Restorative Justice”, British Journal of Criminology 42, str. 469-475. Opšta deklaracija o pravima čoveka, usvojena i proklamovana od strane Generalne Skupštine rezolucijom 217A (III) od 10. decembra 1948. godine. Papić, T. ur. (2002) Zbirka odluka o ljudskim pravima II, odluke Evropskog suda za ljudska prava, Beogradski centar za ljudska prava, Beograd, str. 396-430. United Ntions Standard Minimum Rules for the Administration of Juvenile Justice – Beijing Rules, 1995, Defence for Children International. Zakon o ratifi kaciji Međunarodnog pakta o građanskim i političkim pravima, “Službeni list SFRJ” br. 7/71. Zakon o ratifi kaciji Međunarodnog pakta o ekonomskim, so- cijalnim i kulturnim pravima, “Sl. List SFRJ” br. 7/71. Zakonik o krivičnom postupku, „Sl. List SRJ” 70/2001 i 68/2002; „Sl. glasnik Republike Srbije”, br. 58/2004 od 28. maja 2004. godine; 85/2005; 115/2006. Miomira KOSTIĆ, Ph.D. Setting Standards of Restorative Justice In the article the author deals with the basic theoretical statements and discussions about the practical use of restorative justice. She discusses the questions of introducing and application of restorative justice in order to reach the balance of interests between a victim, society and a delin- quent. There is no unique statement about the re- storative justice concept, so the authors make this concept by listing certain activities with rispect of standards and principles. Also she emphasizes the values of restorative justice process. A part of the article is dedicated to the standards for restorative justice that are harmonized with the international documents of human rights. Keywords: restorative justice, standards, prin- ciples, retributive justice Dr Miomira KOSTIĆ work_it3izdfo3bcbdke4kfbbtrfkly ---- Intergenerational Justice and Climate Change University of Warwick institutional repository This paper is made available online in accordance with publisher policies. Please scroll down to view the document itself. Please refer to the repository record for this item and our policy information available from the repository home page for further information. To see the final version of this paper please visit the publisher’s website. Access to the published version may require a subscription. Author(s): Page, Edward Article Title: Intergenerational Justice and Climate Change Year of publication: 1999 Link to published version: http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/1467-9248.00187 Publisher statement: The definitive version is available at www.blackwell-synergy.com http://www.blackwell-synergy.com/� Intergenerational Justice and Climate Change EDWARD A. PAGE University of Southampton* Global climate change has important implications for the way in which benefits and burdens will be distributed amongst present and future generations. As a result it raises important questions of intergenerational justice. It is shown that there is at least one serious problem for those who wish to approach these questions by utilising familiar principles of justice. This is that such theories often pre-suppose harm-based accounts of injustice which are incompatible with the fact that the very social policies which climatologists and scientists claim will reduce the risks of climate change will also predictably, if indirectly, determine which individuals will live in the future. One proposed solution to this problem is outlined grounded in terms of the notion of collective interests. The issue of global climate change has attracted increasing interest amongst political scientists and theorists in recent years. The complex interactions amongst nation-states which have resulted from moves to construct world-wide, and legally binding, restrictions on greenhouse gas (GHG) emissions is a fascinating source of research for international relations theorists generally, and game theorists in particular.1 * I would like to thank Andrew Williams, John Horton, and an anonymous referee of Political Studies for helpful comments on earlier versions of this article. Moreover, the fact that the future costs of climate change are not expected to be shared evenly amongst nations has 1 For a game theoretical account of climate change politics, see Hugh Ward, ‘Game Theory and the Politics of Global Warming: the State of Play and Beyond’, Political Studies, 44, 5 (1996), 850-71; for the international relations perspective on climate change issues see M. Peterson, Global Warming and Global Politics, (London, Routledge, 1996). 2 attracted the interest of theorists concerned with problems of global justice.2 Recent evidence suggests, for example, that present levels of GHG emissions will have particularly grave consequences both for the integrity of the biosphere and for the well-being of its future human and non-human inhabitants. In its most recent assessment of the global climate change issue, the authoritative Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) concluded not only that ‘the balance of evidence suggests discernible human influence on climate change’, However, one of the most striking set of questions raised by climate change concerns the way in which social, economic and cultural resources should be distributed across generations. 3 but also that the long-term impact of climate change will have a predominantly, if not uniformly, adverse impact on the health, cultural life, and economic prosperity of future human populations.4 In fact, the IPCC went on to conclude that global climate change issues raise ‘particular questions of equity between generations.’5 While the IPCC seem to take it largely for granted that climate change raises questions of intergenerational justice, there have been few systematic attempts to test the robustness of these assumptions (1) across different theories of distributive justice and (2) in the light of some perplexing problems associated with extending the scope of these theories beyond the realm of dealings between contemporaries of the same society. 2 See M. Grubb, ‘Seeking fair weather: ethics and the international debate on climate change’, International Affairs, 71, 3 (1995), 463-96; H. Shue, ‘Avoidable necessity: Global warming, international fairness, and alternative energy’, in I. Shapiro and J. W. DeCew, eds., NOMOS XXXVII: Theory and Practice, (New York, New York University Press, 1995), 239-64; and H. Shue, ‘The Unavoidability of Justice’, in A. Hurrell and B. Kingsbury, eds., The International Politics of the Environment, (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1992), pp.373-97. 3 J.T. Houghton, M.C. Zinyowera, and R.H. Moss, eds., Climate Change 1995: The Science of Climate Change, (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press), 1996, p.5. 4 See A.J. McMichael et al, ‘Human Population Health’, in R.T. Watson, eds., Climate Change 1995: Impacts, Adaptations, and Mitigation of Climate Change, (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1996), pp. 564ff. It is worth noting that at least some of the IPCC’s research findings are controversial. However, even those who are sceptical of the relevance of the IPCC’s findings for questions of social justice, such as Wilfrid Beckerman, do not dispute the fact that climate change will impact upon the distribution of resources across generations to some extent. See W. Beckerman, Small is Stupid: Blowing the whistle on the greens, (London, Duckworth, 1995), pp.90ff. 5 K.J. Arrow et al, ‘Intertemporal Equity, Discounting and Economic Efficiency’, in J.P Bruce, H. Lee, and E. Haites, eds., Climate Change 1995: Economic and Social Dimensions of Climate Change, (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1996), p. 130. This conclusion is consistent with the text of the earlier United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change, according to which those nations party to it ‘should protect the climate system for the benefit of present and future generations of humankind, on the basis of equity and in accordance with their common but differentiated responsibilities and respective capabilities.’ See United Nations Framework Convention on Climate Change, (London, HMSO Books, 1993), p.5. 3 Regarding issue 2, for example, there appears to be a widely held conviction that activities which compound the climate change problem are unjust, or unethical, because they harm generations yet unborn.6 In the next section, I outline briefly a prominent example of an identity-dependent theory of intergenerational justice. Next, I explain how this theory, by virtue of its identity- dependent structure, seems unlikely to generate stringent duties of intergenerational justice - for example, duties which could explain why existing generations should sacrifice certain benefits in order to preserve the climate system for their remote descendants. Next, I argue that whereas we might appeal to an identity-independent theory of intergenerational justice in order to explain the basis of such duties, there are considerations which suggest that it would be worth seeing if some version of the identity-dependent view can be defended. Finally, I develop one line of thought which seeks to do precisely this, which is developed in terms of the notion of collective interests. This paper argues, however, that a unique philosophical puzzle confronts those who wish to explain our responsibilities to future generations, for example regarding the climate change problem, in terms of the language of disadvantages and harms. The central problem developed is that it is unclear how exactly future persons can be harmed, or disadvantaged, by acts or social policies which are necessary conditions of their coming into existence. This presents a serious challenge, it will be argued, for a whole range of accounts of environmental, and intergenerational, justice which assume that actions or policies can only be wrong if they harm, disadvantage or victimise particular human or non-human animals (I call these identity-dependent accounts of justice). Inter gener ational justice as r esour ce conser vation One theory of intergenerational justice which seems consistent with the thought that existing generations owe it to their distant successors not to despoil the natural environment in general, and the climate system in particular, proposes that each generation should hand down to the next a no less abundant share of resources than that which it inherited from previous generations. According to an influential version of this theory proposed by Barry, the consumption of non-renewable natural resources over time ‘should 6 Onora O’Neill, for example, writes that ‘by burning fossil fuels prodigally we accelerate the green-house effect and may dramatically harm successors, who can do nothing to us.’ See O’Neill, Towards Justice and Virtue (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1996), p.115. 4 be compensated for in the sense that later generations should be left no worse off. . . than they would have been without the depletion.’7 Barry comes to this resourcist view by the following line of thought. We might call this the resourcist view of intergenerational justice. 8 It would be unfair to require existing generations to leave all non-renewable resources untouched for the sake of future generations (that is to consume nothing); neither would it be possible for each generation to replicate in every detail the non- renewable resources it exhausts. However, it would appear to be a sound principle to aim for that existing generations ought not act so as to worsen the position of future generations by depleting non-renewable resources with no compensatory action or recompense. The fundamental issue for a theory of intergenerational justice, he thinks, is the appropriate consumption of non-renewable natural resources across time. When reserves of non- renewable resources (such as oil or natural gas) are depleted, the costs of extracting and then using these resources to generate electricity to heat homes, power cars, and run machinery are increased for future generations. There are also costs imposed upon these generations in virtue of the side-effects of depleting these resources, such as global climate change, air pollution and destruction of the ozone layer. As a consequence, it is crucial to establish how much existing generations may deplete stocks of non-renewable resources without violating the requirements of intergenerational justice. The idea of making recompense, however, typically leaves it open for a given compensation for a depleted resource, X, to be compensated by the provision of a given commensurable resource, Y - so long as this compensation enables the recipient to be no worse off than they would have been had the original resource, X, not been used up. Perhaps the most obvious example of such compensation in the intergenerational context would be the way in which improvements in technology (energy efficiency, for example) appear to compensate for losses of natural non-renewable resources (energy resources such as coal, for example). So long as we regard the climate system as a sort of ‘open access resource’ in its own right, it appears that resourcism will generate extensive obligations on the part of 7 B. Barry, ‘The Ethics of Resource Depletion’, in Democracy, Power and Justice, (Oxford, Clarendon, 1989), p.519 - emphasis added. 8 Barry, ‘The ethics of resource depletion’, pp.515ff. 5 existing generations (1) not to damage the climate system by continued profligate GHG emissions, (2) not to deplete non-renewable natural resources which are sources of GHGs, or (3) not to bring about the destruction of certain natural resources (such as coastal land) through climate change unless these actions are offset by an appropriate amount of compensation. Inter gener ational r esour cism and the non-identity pr oblem As a test for Barry’s theory of intergenerational justice, next consider the case of the Two Climate Change Policies: A choice must be made between two mutually exclusive, and exhaustive, climate change policies. The first, the Depletion Policy, involves a continuing commitment to non-renewable energy sources and associated high levels of GHG emissions with no commitment to any offsetting compensation measures for the sake of future generations. The second, the Conservation Policy, involves a move towards heavier reliance on renewable energy sources, tight restrictions on GHG emissions, as well as certain compensatory measures for the sake of future generations (such as increased investment in schemes to protect coastal areas which are vulnerable to climate change induced sea-level rises). Adopting the Conservation policy, it is known, will limit the damage caused by climate change. The Depletion Policy, though, would demand little or no sacrifice of present persons, and, because it would not check the increase of human originating GHG emissions, would have, relative to the Conservation Policy, more serious repercussions on human well-being (as associated with the social costs of adapting to higher temperatures and sea-levels, for example). In fact, it is known with some confidence that, after one or two centuries after the choice has been made, many of the people who would later live if the Depletion Policy is chosen will enjoy a significantly lower quality of life than those who would live if the Conservation Policy is adopted. However, the long- term disadvantages associated with choosing Depletion are not so severe that the persons who will come into existence if this option is chosen will lead lives 6 which are not worth living - i.e. they will not on balance regret that these people had ever been born. Next, consider the following line of argument which seems to undermine the reasoning behind many people’s intuitive objections to the Depletion Policy.9 As a consequence of the profound impact it will have on even the smallest details of all people’s lives, whatever decision is made in regard to the Conservation and Depletion policies will predictably, if indirectly, affect who mates with whom and when, and thus which individuals will be born in the future. This is because all persons owe their existence to the coming together of a singular egg and a singular sperm - and this ‘coming together’ is highly sensitive to antecedent events. In fact, after a few generations, and depending on which policy we choose, completely different sets of people will come into existence and these sets of people will owe their existence to this prior choice (they would not have been born if this choice had not been made). Moreover, as we can predict with some accuracy that the adoption of neither policy will result in any of our distant successors leading lives which are not worth living, it appears that choosing Depletion over Conservation will not result in any particular future person being harmed. On the other hand, such a choice would benefit many in the present generation by doing so, as even the limited sacrifices which Conservation will demand of existing persons will be on balance harmful. It seems then that the policy that ought to be adopted is, perhaps counter- intuitively, the Depletion Policy. Is there an objection to this line of argument and, if so, what is it? The need to answer these questions gives rise to what has been called the non-identity problem10 9 Various versions of this argument have been put forward, but by far the most influential is Parfit’s. See D. Parfit, Reasons and Persons, (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1984), pp.351ff. and the way in which we answer them will have great significance for the way in which we approach issues of environmental, and intergenerational, justice. Take Barry’s resourcist view. The non-identity problem appears to pose a severe challenge for this view because it appeals to a strong connection between the requirements of justice on the one side, and the notions of harm and disadvantage on the other. Barry holds that failures to compensate future generations for deficits in the resource base they enjoy which are brought about by 10 Parfit, Reasons and Persons, p.359. 7 the actions of previous generations are unjust, and that they are unjust because such actions render people worse off than they otherwise would have been. But the non-identity problem demonstrates that there will be few, if any, cases where a future person will be rendered worse off by their ancestors’ profligate emissions of GHGs, because these people would never have existed had these profligate actions not been performed. This is not a problem which Barry’s view faces alone. All views of intergenerational justice which endorse what has become known as the ‘contractualist’ view of morality will be prone to the non-identity problem. According to contractualism, the source of moral motivation is ‘the desire to be able to justify one’s actions to others on grounds they could not reasonably reject’11 and an act is wrong only if its performance ‘would be disallowed by any system of rules for the general regulation of behaviour which no one could reasonably reject as a basis for informed, unforced general agreement.’12 For a person to reasonably reject (or raise a decisive objection to) an act or social policy on the contractualist view, this person must (1) be disadvantaged or harmed by it in some way and (2) they must have a complaint grounded in this disadvantage which is unanswerable (we might call this the Unanswerable Complaints Requirement).13 The problem with applying the unanswerable complaints requirement to the Conservation-Depletion choice, though, is that there appear to be no particular people here whom our acts will affect for the worse, and will thus have a complaint against us, if we choose Depletion. Moreover, as even mildly conservationist policies will require some sacrifices of existing persons, it seems that if any people have unanswerable complaints here it will be people who belong to the present generation (for example, those living in 11 T.M. Scanlon, ‘Contractualism and Utilitarianism’, in A. Sen and B. Williams, eds., Utilitarianism and Beyond, (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1982), p. 116. 12 T.M. Scanlon, ‘Contractualism and Utilitarianism’, p.110. Barry endorses the contractualist view in both Theories of Justice, (Berkeley, University of California Press, 1989), pp. 284ff; and Justice as Impartiality, (Oxford, Clarendon, 1995), pp. 67-72. It is worth noting that Barry does not address the difficulties which the non-identity problem pose for his view in any of his published work on intergenerational and environmental justice, although in a recent article he does observe that contractual thinking cannot readily explain our duties to future persons or the non-human world. Thus he remarks that although ‘the interests of people in the future should have no less weight than those of people in the present’, it does not appear that ‘the contractual apparatus is useful in this context; it throws up more problems than it solves.’ See ‘Contractual Justice: a Modest Defence’, Utilitas, 8 (1996), p.365. Barry does not go on to state how he thinks we might reconcile contractualism with stringent duties of intergenerational justice, though it appears to be his desire to do so in the last of his three volume work A Treatise on Social Justice. 13 See Parfit, Reasons and Persons, who observes that on the Scanlonian view ‘an act cannot be wrong unless it will affect someone in a way that cannot be justified - unless there will be some complainant whose complaint cannot be answered’ (p.523). 8 the developing world who will suffer if their economies fail to keep growing) - and these complaints will be raised against the adoption of the Conservation Policy, not the Depletion Policy).14 I have focused, here, on the questions raised by the non-identity problem for theories of intergenerational justice, such as Barry’s, which explicitly endorse the contractualist view. However, similar questions will be raised for numerous other theories which appeal, at least in part, to the way in which acts or social policies harm particular persons when they are extended to deal with questions of intergenerational justice. It would appear to call into doubt, for example, recent attempts to use Locke’s well-known second proviso - according to which acquisitions of natural resources must leave ‘enough, and as good left in common for others’ - to ground stringent requirements of environmental conservation. 15 Theories such as these, which can be described as identity-dependent theories, direct us to make particular human beings, or animals, healthier or happier or rescue people from harm or disadvantage, particularly if these disadvantages arise through no fault of their own. Identity-dependent theories can be contrasted with identity-independent theories, according to which it can be wrong to perform acts or adopt social policies, even if they do not harm any particular persons. Such theories direct us to promote health or happiness, and to eliminate poverty or disease from an impersonal point of view (that is for reasons quite apart from the way in which particular individuals are affected by these phenomena). One way of illustrating the dilemma that the non-identity problem poses for identity-dependent theories of environmental and intergenerational justice, is to note that it tempts the proponents of these theories into holding four, mutually inconsistent, beliefs. According to these beliefs: 14 The possibility that climate change policies could well have as damaging an effect on the well-being of the present poor as they do beneficial effects for the well-being of future generations is raised by Beckerman and Malkin. The authors observe that ‘Global warming is far more glamorous and telegenic, of course, than the need for better toilets and drains in the Third World. But if we truly care about the welfare of our fellow world citizens, it is these kinds of environmental issues upon which we must focus our attention.’ See W. Beckerman and J. Malkin, ‘How much does global warming matter?’, The Public Interest, 114 (1994), pp.15-16. 15 J. Locke, Two Treatises of Government, (London, Everyman, 1924), Book II, Ch.V, Sec. 27, p.130. See also R. Elliot, ‘Future Generations, Locke’s Proviso and Libertarian Justice’, Journal of Applied Philosophy, 3 (1986), pp.217ff. 9 (A) adopting the Depletion Policy is wrong. (B) an act or social policy can be wrong only if it harms or disadvantages a particular person (C) an act or social policy harms or disadvantages a particular person only if it makes them worse off than they would have been had the act not been performed (D) the adoption of the Depletion Policy is a remote, but necessary, condition of the Depletion People coming into existence. If we are inclined towards an identity-dependent view, it seems that we must abandon either belief B or C (or possibly both) if we are to construct an account which explains why choosing the Depletion Policy in the above case would violate some requirement of justice.16 However, both B and C appear to have a great deal of intuitive appeal. David Heyd, for example, has argued recently for the view that the price of abandoning either of these beliefs, and with them the identity-dependent view of justice, is simply too high.17 Endorsing a view which he calls generocentrism, Heyd claims that obligations of social justice only can be owed to persons whose identities lie beyond the reach of the non-identity problem. But because persons whose identities do not depend on present decisions will almost invariably belong to the present generation, Heyd claims that we have no obligations of justice to the vast majority of future individuals. If this rigidly identity-dependent view could be defended, it would appear that the non-identity problem has massive implications for both the nature of intergenerational and environmental justice. It implies, for example, that depletionist acts or social policies which result in the emission of huge amounts of GHGs into the atmosphere, and a lowering of the quality of life of future generations, are neither unjust nor immoral.18 The limits of the non-identity pr oblem 16 I put aside the possibility of revising belief D in order to retain beliefs A, B and C - a move which seems at the very least inconsistent with the pre-eminent theories of personal identity. See Parfit, Reasons and Persons, pp.351-55. 17 Heyd, Genethics: Moral issues in the creation of persons, Berkeley, University of California Press, pp. 80ff. 18 It is worth noting that the non-identity problem appears to call into question the idea of obligations to both future humans and non-humans. This is because the identity of particular non-human animals will be as contingent on events which pre-date their existence as their future human counterparts. 10 Even if we suppose that the non-identity problem is of relevance for debates about our obligations to future generations, and the issue of environmental justice in more general terms, it does appear that considerations of non-identity are not problematic for all theories of environmental concern. One way of explaining why this is the case is to see how the problem relates to different ways of theorising about the environment. In what has become the standard taxonomy of such theorising, we might distinguish between anthropocentric, zoocentric, and ecocentric modes of environmental thought.19 Anthropocentric theories are those which attribute value only to states of human beings. One prominent example is the ‘green theory of value’ proposed by Robert Goodin. According to this view, the value of the natural world can be traced only ‘to its value to human beings and the place it occupies in their lives.’20 Zoocentric theories, by contrast, attribute value only to states of sentient creatures, including human beings. The idea here is that the desire to restrict the concerns of environmental justice to the well-being of human beings represents a sort of ‘human chauvinism’ 21 which ignores the fact that species membership is essentially ‘a morally irrelevant difference between individuals.’22 According to Singer, for example, if we are committed to the fundamental principle that each human being’s interests must be treated with equal concern and respect, we are also committed to accepting this principle of equality ‘as a sound moral basis for relations with those outside our own species [such as] non-human animals.’23 Finally, ecocentric theories reject the idea that the natural environment is only valuable to the extent that it provides a context for the flourishing of humans or other sentient creatures. In contrast, this mode of thought presupposes that components of the 19 See, for example, Brian Barry, Justice as Impartiality, pp.20ff. 20 R. Goodin Green Political Theory, (Cambridge, Polity, 1992), pp.42-3. A similarly anthropocentric stance on the value of the natural environment is endorsed by the World Commission on Environment and Development’s influential report Our Common Future, (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1987). In the foreword to this report, Gro Harlem Brundlandt argues that human well-being ‘is the ultimate goal of all environment and development and development policies’ (p.xiv). 21 See R. and V. Routley, ‘Against the Inevitability of Human Chauvinism’, in Robert Elliot, ed., Environmental Ethics, (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1995), pp.104ff. 22 Elliot, Environmental Ethics, p.9. 23 P. Singer, Practical Ethics, (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1993), p.55. 11 natural world such as plant life, and possibly the biotic community as a whole, possess value independently of humans or animals.24 I do not think it is necessary to take a stand on which of these modes of theorising best captures our concerns about the environment, or indeed intergenerational justice, in order to realise that the non-identity problem only calls into question the scope of certain varieties of anthropocentric and zoocentric (and possibly ecocentric) theorising, namely, those which appeal to ethical categories that make essential reference to how things are for particular individual humans, other sentient creatures, or particular natural objects. In short, the distinction between identity-dependent and identity-independent theories of justice cuts across the distinction between different ways of theorising about environmental concerns and values (of which the anthropocentric, zoocentric, and ecocentric views are the most widely discussed). Nevertheless, there are at least three considerations which support the view that the non-identity problem is at least worthy of more attention than most environmental political philosophers have given it in recent years. First, even if we reject the view that identity-dependent theorising captures the whole of the story of intergenerational or environmental justice, it seems likely that it at least plays some part in this story. As a result it seems worth exploring the limits of such theorising. Second, environmental theories which makes no reference to how things are for particular individual entities, such as impersonal utilitarianism or biotic holism, are highly contentious to say the least. Parfit, for example, has done much to demonstrate that applying identity-independent utilitarian principles to questions of intergenerational distribution leads to paradoxical results.25 Moreover, the idea behind biotic holism, that ethical standing be extended to components of the biosphere (such as rocks, trees, species of plant or animal life) - or even the biosphere as a whole - seems wildly counter-intuitive to many.26 24 See P. Taylor, Respect for Nature, (New Jersey, Princeton University Press, 1986); K. Goodpaster, ‘On being morally considerable’, Journal of Philosophy, 78 (1978), pp.308ff. 25 One problem which Parfit raises is that, in line with the duty to maximise social utility across generations, utilitarianism could require us to adopt environmental policies which lead to a huge number of people existing in the future who lead lives of poor overall quality instead of policies which lead to a much small number of people existing in the future who lead lives of a much higher quality. See Parfit, Reasons and Persons, pp.381ff. 26 For criticism of the ecocentric view, see A. Brennan, ‘Ecological Theory and Value in Nature’, in R. Elliot, ed., Environmental Ethics, pp.195ff. 12 Third, as noted earlier, much theorising about the environment and intergenerational justice remains stubbornly tied both to considerations of harm and vinctimhood on the one side, and the interests, needs, rights, and desires of particular sentient creatures on the other. This is revealed in the brief discussion of Barry’s and Scanlon’s views above, but an additional example of note arises from the work of Shue which specifically addresses the issue of climate change. Shue has claimed recently, for example, that we should conceive of the harmful effects of climate change as analogous to those of passive smoking, the idea being that both the activity of smokers, and of profligate emitters of GHGs, render other non-smokers and non-emitters worse off through no fault of their own.27 Obligations to futur e collectivities Shue, however, fails to acknowledge that the fact that future persons owe their very existence to the profligate actions of previous generations in these cases means that they cannot apparently complain that they have been harmed, or rendered worse off, by them. In this respect, the analogy between the effects of passive smoking on the one side, and the effects of depletionist policies on future generations on the other, seems unsound. In this section of the paper I propose that a limited appeal to the interests, rights, or moral value, of certain human (or possibly non-human animal) collectivities can solve the non- identity problem in a limited, though important, range of cases; and as a result this appeal can explain, from an identity-dependent point of view, what is wrong with implementing policies which will have adverse long-term effects. I call views of intergenerational justice grounded in this appeal to human communities group-centred views. Group-centred views are special instances of identity-dependent views, such as Barry’s or Scanlon’s, which have been extended to include human (or animal) groups as being the subjects of moral consideration. these different views relate to each other is explored in figure 1 (page 14) Climate change and the claims of future collectivities The climate changes predicted by the IPCC and other researchers are expected to alter the cultural and social fabric of certain nations. There is possibly no better example of this 27 Shue, ‘Avoidable necessity: Global Warming, International Fairness, and Alternative Energy’, pp.245-6. 13 than the way in which these changes are expected to cause significant sea-level rises in the coming decades and centuries. In its latest assessment, the IPCC concluded that there will be an increase in global mean sea-levels of between 20cm and 86cm (with a ‘best estimate’ of 49cm) on 1990 levels by the year 2100.28 Moreover, it also predicts that this will have serious consequences for many nations in the future, but in particular for developing countries which are entirely, or have regions which are, low-lying. For example, these sea-level rises are expected to damage coastal cropland, and displace millions of persons from low-lying and coastal communities. Just some of the low-lying nations that the IPCC thinks are in most danger are the north-east coastal nations of Latin America, Bangladesh, Egypt and Holland.29 28 See R.A. Warrick et al, ‘Changes in Sea-level’, in J. Houghton et al, eds., Climate Change 1995: The Science of Climate Change, p.385. 29 See L. Bijlsma et al, ‘Coastal Zones and Small Islands’, in R.T. Watson et al, eds., Climate Change 1995: Impacts, Adaptations, and Mitigation of Climate Change, 289-324. The authors project that sea-level rise will have ‘negative effects on a number of sectors, including tourism, freshwater supply and quality, fisheries and aquaculture, agriculture, human settlements, financial services, and human health’ (p.292). 14 (Q1) Can an act be wrong if it does not affect any particular value bearing individual for the worse? No The Identity-Dependent View Yes The Identity-Independent View The Narrow Identity-Dependent (or Individualistic) View (Q2) Can an act be wrong if it affects a particular human or animal community (rather than any particular human or non-human animal) for the worse? No Yes The Wide Identity-Dependent (or Group-Centred) View Figure 1: Identity-Dependent and Identity-Independent Theories Perhaps the most disconcerting examples of nations vulnerable to sea-level rises, however, are the small island states of the South Pacific. The IPCC singles out these nations for special attention because of the especially, if not uniformly, adverse effects of sea-level rises on these states, including, in the worst case scenario, the possibility of complete disappearance. The combined effect of warming and sea-level rises on such states is expected to result in reduced soil fertility, reduced availability of agricultural land, and higher levels of soil erosion. It will be massively expensive to undertake even moderate adaptive responses for all of these effects, and even if the resources could be found (from international humanitarian assistance, for example) the costs to various communities in terms of maintaining access to traditional ways of life, and adapting to new ways of living, would be huge. These are all projections which the IPCC make with some confidence.30 30 See Bijlsma et al, ‘Coastal Zones and Small Islands’, pp. 296-98. See also E. Charles et al, A Future for Small States: Overcoming Vulnerability, London, Commonwealth Secretariat, 1997, pp.67ff. 15 Suppose the IPCC’s fears about the ‘best estimate’ figure of global sea-level rise of a half a meter by the year 2100 are proved accurate. Consider the case of The Displaced Islanders. Towards the end of the 21st century, the elders of a Pacific island state have assembled to assess the damage which climate change has caused their small community. In line with the IPCC’s projections, their island has been partially submerged by the Pacific Ocean, and their agricultural industry partially destroyed by a combination of soil erosion and soil infertility. Because of the lack of employment prospects and general social upheaval, moreover, the indigenous population has been cut to a small percentage of its twentieth century level. Finally, because of the combined impact of population displacement and other impacts, many cultural practices - practices which had been handed down through the generations - have been abandoned. The community, the elders agreed, was on the verge of collapse. Let us put aside the economic, social and health impacts of climate change on existing islanders, and in particular the important issues of international justice which this case raises. Has the island community itself been harmed by - can a complaint be made on its behalf against - the failure of previous generations to implement GHG limiting policies which may have prevented the unsavoury effects of climate change imagined above? According to the group-centred view, there is at least some basis to say that it has. The idea is that, despite the fact that no particular islander who exists in the future where depletionist policies had been adopted would also have existed had conservationist policies been adopted, various island groups and associations would exist whichever sort of policy had been chosen, and the interests of these groups are deserving of concern and respect in their own right. Here it is the interests of the many groups whose existence and flourishing are bound up with the island’s natural environment which generate certain moral requirements which we can say were violated by the Depletion Policy’s adoption. Suppose that the community was, prior to the sea-level rise, a traditional community dedicated to preserving a rich cultural and linguistic heritage. As the warming, and consequent sea-level rises, would result in the impoverishment of the islanders’ 16 linguistic and cultural heritage (most of the population bar the Elders, let us suppose, have fled to the mainland and now need to speak a different language in order to seek a living) the interests of the islanders as a collectivity might be thought to have been harmed by this. Because it assumes that there is inherent value in the survival of certain groups and that these groups possess valid moral claims qua groups, the group-centred view appears to avoid problems of non-identity. This is because the conditions of existence of many future groups (such as states, nations or cultures) will often be robust to the point that they will not be affected by environmental policy decisions made in the past. Obviously there are a number of simplifying assumptions being made here, such as the assumption that many of the adverse impacts of climate change on future populations can be prevented by the concerted efforts of present persons, governments and international institutions. However, the central idea - that climate change will in certain instances jeopardise the survival of certain communities and traditional patterns of life quite apart from the effects it will have on the individual members of these cultures - appears to be a plausible one.31 It is worth comparing the view proposed here with recent contributions to the issue of the rights or claims of minority cultures. It has recently been argued that the adoption of certain acts or social policies can be wrong by virtue of undermining the needs which particular individuals have to access a flourishing cultural or communal context within which to pursue their personal life-plans or conceptions of the good. For example, in his treatment of the issue of the claims of minority communities, Kymlicka argues that ‘membership in a cultural structure is what enables individual freedom, what enables meaningful choices about how to lead one’s life.’ 32 Kymlicka goes on to claim that the moral importance of individual freedom is such that persons belonging to disadvantaged minority cultures should be afforded additional rights and resources to compensate for the disadvantages they face as a result of membership in a minority culture. But while these rights are collective, in the sense that they are exercised collectively rather than individually, they are nonetheless individual rights in the sense that they are grounded in the interests of particular persons.33 31 The IPCC certainly think so, for they expect that ‘adaptation to sea-level-rise and climate change will involve important trade-offs, which could include environmental, social, cultural values’ (p.292). By contrast, according to the group-centred view, the 32 W. Kymlicka, Liberalism, Community, and Culture, (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1989), p.208; and Multicultural Citizenship, (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1995), pp.80ff. 33 See Kymlicka, Multicultural Citizenship, pp.34ff. 17 communities which future people will belong to are deserving of concern and respect in their own right; and if present actions have the result either that these communities die out altogether, or are damaged in the sense that various communal practices are undermined, they are morally objectionable at least in this one important respect.34 In this regard, the group-centred view shares much in common with Charles Taylor’s work on multiculturalism and the politics of recognition, and in particular on the issue of the value of communities. Taylor denies that the worth of communities is derived from the value it has in securing the ‘cultural needs’ of individuals, such as their seeking to give meaning to their lives. He gives two reasons for this. First, Kymlicka’s individualistic view neglects the moral importance of various communities qua communities. The idea here is that communities are often not merely associations of value-bearing individuals, but rather moral entities in their own right. Secondly, the individualistic view cannot make space for the way in which many persons have the intense desire that the community, or communities, they belong to continue to survive and flourish for reasons unrelated to the positive impact that this will have on their own well- being, or on the well-being of their compatriots taken as individuals. 35 As such, Taylor argues that Kymlicka’s individualistic view might be valid perhaps ‘for existing people who find themselves trapped within a culture under pressure, and can flourish within it or not at all. But it doesn’t justify measures designed to ensure survival through indefinite future generations. For the populations concerned, however, that is what is at stake.’36 34 The idea of group-centred requirements of intergenerational justice might also be contrasted with the more obviously ‘communitarian’ idea that present persons should protect the conditions of communal flourishing because the communities which they belong to are in fact essential components of their identity as persons. Consider, for example, the communitarian theory of intergenerational justice defended in A. de Shalit’s Why Posterity Matters, (London, Routledge, 1996), especially Ch.1. The idea is also to be contrasted with recent contributions to the ‘deep ecology’ mode of environmental thought, according to which duties of environmental conservation flow from the fact that human identity is not merely moulded by membership in human communities, but in addition by it’s connection to natural processes and the biosphere itself. See, for example, W. Fox, Toward a Transpersonal Ecology, (Boston, Shambala, 1990). By contrast, the key to the group-centred view is the idea that adopting social policies which undermine the integrity or viability of certain human, or non-human animal, communities is morally regrettable because this fails to afford these communities with the respect that they deserve as moral entities, not that they are regrettable in virtue of undermining the motivations of self-transcendence entertained by existing human beings. According to the terminology introduced earlier, and developed in figure 1, it appears that 35 C. Taylor, ‘The Politics of Recognition’, in A. Guttman, ed., Multiculturalism: Examining the Politics of Recognition, (Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1994), pp. 40-41. 36 Taylor, ‘The Politics of Recognition’, p. 41. 18 Taylor is advocating a widely identity-dependent (or group-centred) view to Kymlicka’s narrowly identity-dependent (or individualistic) view. One advantage associated with embracing the group-centred view is that, in virtue of retaining an identity-dependent structure, it appears readily reconcilable with the views of both Barry and Scanlon. Recall that, for Scanlon, an act is wrong only if its performance ‘would be disallowed by any system of rules for the general regulation of behaviour which no one could reasonably reject as a basis for informed, unforced general agreement.’37 However, contractualists do not appear to be committed to the idea that the complaints that they view as unanswerable must be restricted to those arising from harms, or wrongs, done to particular persons. This is demonstrated by Scanlon’s understanding of the scope of contractualism, according to which (1) moral beings must possess a good in the sense that ‘that there be a clear sense in which things can be said to go better or worse for that being’, and (2) moral beings must ‘constitute a point of view; that is there be such a thing as what it is like to be that being.’ It was argued above that contractualism and the unanswerable complaints principle this view of morality endorses, seem problematic in the context of non-identity cases such as the Depletion-Conservation choice, as the Depletion People, taken one by one, do not appear to have a legitimate complaint against the Depletion Policy’s adoption. 38 While I have not the space here to construct a more positive defence for this line of thought, it is worth mentioning that many peoples’ moral intuitions certainly point in this direction. Consider, for example, the widespread intuition that the deaths of large numbers of persons from small indigenous communities (which result in the deaths of these communities) are more regrettable from the moral point of view than equivalent numbers of deaths of unrelated individuals. In any case, the suggestion is that we ought to think These two conditions must hold, Scanlon thinks, for us to be able to hold that the notion of justification can be applied to an entity. But while there are certainly differences between the ‘points of view’ of particular human beings on the one side, and particular groups of human beings on the other, there seems to be no insurmountable barrier in the way of those who wish to argue that there can be such a thing as a group point of view, or perspective on things, or that things can go better or worse for at least some groups. 37 Scanlon, ‘Contractualism and Utilitarianism’, p. 110. 38 Scanlon, ‘Contractualism and Utilitarianism’, pp. 113-14. 19 seriously about revising Scanlon’s account of moral reasoning to read that ‘an act is wrong only if it affects some particular individual or group in a way that cannot be justified.’ I have space to mention only one problem with using the group-centred view to explain how an identity-dependent objection to depletionist policies might be defended in the light of considerations of non-identity. Suppose that a course of action which we think will harm a certain future group’s interests would also be a necessary condition of that group’s existence. In such cases it might be that the approach will be plagued by a new group-centred version of the non-identity problem, which we might call the extended non- identity problem. This new version of the non-identity problem suggests that a representative of some community who claims that the interests of their community had been harmed by the profligate environmental activities of past generations would encounter great problems in defending this view. In such circumstances it seems that the group-centred view could not be used to ground an identity-dependent objection to these activities; and as a result it would seem that only identity-independent considerations would stand in the way of the claim that it would not be wrong for depletionist policies to be adopted by existing generations. It is, of course, worth noting that conditions of non-identity will obtain much less regularly in the case of groups than in the case of individual persons. This is because the identities of many groups and communities are more robust - nations, for example, typically outlive their individual members many times over. As a result, the extended non- identity problem only partly rebuts the group-centred view. The conclusion we should take from this, I think, that this view does indeed offer at least some defence of an identity- dependent environmental, and intergenerational, ethic. ADPC7.tmp University of Warwick institutional repository work_iwnndj7nazak7e6zltpvohwvzq ---- Microsoft Word - abc_cpsfinal122010   1 Determinants of Attitudes towards Transitional Justice: An Empirical Analysis of the Spanish Case Paloma Aguilar, Laia Balcells and Héctor Cebolla1 Forthcoming: Comparative Political Studies Vol 44, Issue 10 (October 2011) Abstract: Much has been said about the institutional determinants of transitional justice (TJ), yet we still know little about the determinants of citizens' attitudes towards restorative policies aimed at addressing human rights violations of the past. This paper draws on an original survey of a representative sample of Spanish citizens conducted in 2008. One year earlier, the Spanish socialist government had approved the so-called "Law of Historical Memory", aimed at providing restitution for victims of the Spanish Civil War (1936-1939) and the Francoist dictatorship (1939-1975). We analyze individual-level attitudes towards a set of TJ policies (i.e. truth commissions, trials, and symbolic reparations) in a comprehensive overview of the field. We study the effect of different sets of variables: individual socio-demographic and ideological factors, family and socialization variables, and context-related factors. Individual ideology, family victimization during the dictatorship and regional context appear as highly relevant in explaining individual attitudes towards TJ policies. Keywords: Transitional Justice, Spain, Memory, Victimization, Socialization                                                              1 Paloma Aguilar is Associate Professor of Political Science at UNED (Spain); Laia Balcells is researcher at Institute for Economic Analysis, CSIC (Barcelona, Spain); Héctor Cebolla is Assistant Professor of Sociology, UNED (Spain). This paper has benefited from comments and suggestions made by Juan Linz, Roger Petersen, Gemma Sala, Elisabeth Wood, the members of the Transitional Justice panel at the Midwest Political Science Association Meeting (2009), and the participants in the 4th MIT-Harvard-Yale Civil Conflict Conference (2009). We thank the CIS for conducting the survey, as well as the people in the Research Department for giving us extremely valuable feedback. We also thank Eudald Lerga, Ana Arjona, David Backer and Pablo De Greiff for their helpful comments and suggestions. The usual caveat applies.     2 1. Introduction The expression “transitional justice” (hereafter, TJ) refers to a set of procedures that are predominantly adopted during democratization periods –but also sometimes when democracy has been consolidated (Aguilar, 2008a; Thoms et al., 2008)– in order to deal with atrocities committed by the former regime or during a violent conflict. TJ procedures fall into three broad categories: (1) justice measures aimed at punishing former perpetrators for human rights violations or depriving them of illegitimate privileges; (2) policies aimed at providing material and/or symbolic reparation for victims; and (3) truth revelation procedures.1 The study of TJ policies is a burgeoning field of social research, but there are still a number of lacunae to be filled. For example, while the vast majority of the literature on TJ has focused on explaining the institutional determinants of these policies or on the normative discussion about their desirability,2 there has been little research on public opinion regarding TJ. In some existing works, the opinion of citizens has been inferred from the pressures exerted by social organizations (Skaar, 1999). This is problematic, because it cannot be assumed that there is a direct relationship between the demands promoted by organizations or pressure groups and the general preferences of the citizenry.3 Moreover, many of the existing scholarly contributions on bottom-up demands for TJ draw on ethnographic research including interviews and/or observational participation (Theidon, 2006; Ferreira, 1999), interviews with specific focus groups (Grodsky, 2008; Martín Beristain, 2008; Strover and Weinstein, 2004; ICTJ, 2004), or interviews with particular subgroups of the overall population, e.g. victims (Espinoza Cuevas, et al. 2003; ICTJ, 2008) or pressure groups (Backer 2003). In short, barring very few exceptions, scholars have not relied on systematic generalizable evidence of individual attitudes towards TJ policies.4 In this paper, we   3 make a two-fold empirical contribution to this literature: first, we explore data from a hitherto unexploited representative survey of the Spanish population, which we designed and was implemented by the Spanish Centro de Investigaciones Sociológicas (hereafter, CIS) in April 2008; second, this survey is a monographic study, which provides us with detailed information on different TJ measures (i.e. commissions, trials and symbolic reparations), as well as on a number of independent and control variables. This type of fine-grained data is a valuable resource from which we gain empirical leverage. At the theoretical level, this paper contributes to a better understanding of TJ by presenting a set of hypotheses on the determinants of individual-level attitudes to these policies, which are grounded in TJ literature and also in the literature on victimization and intergenerational transmission of identities. The latter is particularly relevant for understanding the Spanish case, where the most traumatic and violent events are not recent (the Civil War ended 70 years ago, the dictatorship more than 30 years ago), and therefore a vast majority of the population did not experience the violations at first hand. Even though we focus on the Spanish case, we intend to generate implications for other transitional/post-transitional countries that share some basic characteristics with Spain. This paper is organized as follows: in section 2, we introduce the Spanish case and outline its importance for the study of transitional and post-transitional justice; in section 3, we present the theoretical framework and hypotheses, which we empirically test in section 4. To conclude, we discuss our findings and their implications for other cases.   4 2. Transitional Justice in Spain The Spanish case is particularly appropriate for TJ research: the severe brutality and prolonged violations perpetrated by the Franco regime against those on the losing side in the Civil War (1936–1939), and against all those who subsequently refused to comply with its dictates (1939–1975), are well-known. Throughout the civil conflict, tens of thousands of people on both sides lost their lives as a result of both legal and extrajudicial executions.5 However, political violence continued during the early years of the postwar period; estimations suggest that the Franco regime executed approximately 50,000 people, that the number of prisoners in concentration camps amounted to 300,000, and that hundreds of thousands were forced into exile. Throughout Franco’s entire rule, tens of thousands of people who had been expelled from their jobs after the war as a result of their ideological leanings were systematically denied reinstatement. The regime also refused to offer pensions or any compensation whatsoever not only to war-disabled veterans and civilians, but also to the widows and orphans of defeated combatants. Likewise, political parties, trade unions and private individuals had their assets seized simply for having sympathized with the Second Republic (1931–1936); meanwhile, those who had supported the victors enjoyed numerous perks and privileges. After Franco’s death, the presence of the traumatic memory of the Civil War and the obsessive desire to avoid its repetition encouraged the main political actors and the majority of Spanish citizens to look to the future by putting aside the thorniest aspects of the past. It was firmly believed that this was the only way to ensure a peaceful transition to democracy (Aguilar, 2002, 2008b). As in other cases –Chile, Uruguay and Hungary–, political elites reached a tacit agreement to leave the dictatorial past out of the political debate. In this context, the Parliament enacted the Amnesty Law of 15   5 October 1977, whose purpose was to free political prisoners and to shield the dictatorial past from any judicial proceedings. Among the myriad possible TJ policies that could have been adopted during the transition to democracy, only material reparation measures targeting Civil War losers were approved. These policies were limited and fragmented. TJ measures such as official condemnation of the dictatorship, symbolic measures aimed at the reparation of all the victims of the dictatorship, the creation of a truth commission, or the quashing of Francoist trials -not to mention bringing perpetrators of human rights violations to trial- were never implemented. Nevertheless, when most Spaniards thought that the most painful episodes of their history had been buried once and for all, the past erupted again: in 2000 a private association devoted to the task of locating and exhuming mass graves dating from the Civil War (called the Asociación para la Recuperación de la Memoria Histórica) triggered a social and political debate about the shortcomings of previous TJ policies.6 In this context, the conservative social and State-wide political forces (e.g. the Partido Popular) positioned themselves against “digging into the past”. In contrast, the most progressive political parties and social associations (e.g. the Partido Socialista Obrero Español and the political federation led by the former Communists, Izquierda Unida) were in favor of them. The most important quantitative and qualitative leap forward in relation to TJ legislation took place during the 2004-2008 legislative term, especially with the passing of “Law 52/2007, of 26th December,” which “recognizes and broadens the rights and establishes measures in favor of those who suffered persecution or violence during the Civil War and the dictatorship”.7 Our survey was conducted in the immediate aftermath of the heated debate that accompanied the passing of this law. In this context, Spaniards had diverging opinions   6 towards TJ measures; we wonder on what explains them. Firstly, one could argue that individual characteristics such as ideology influenced opinions on the issue: leftist sympathizers and militants were probably more supportive of a law that was being promoted by a left-wing party. Secondly, personal experiences that proved relevant in explaining preferences towards TJ in other contexts8 could only partially explain these attitudes; most of the Spanish population in 2007 had not experienced the Civil War at first hand, while people under the age of 30 did not even have experience of the dictatorship. Thirdly, since reparation policies in the 2007 “Law of Historical Memory” did not focus on monetary compensations for victimized people, greed or self-interest were irrelevant in this context. Finally, regional factors could also have been important: people living in particular regions may have had different perspectives on TJ owing to their different collective histories during the Civil War and the dictatorship, and also because of their current ethnic identities. 3. Theoretical Framework In this paper, we argue that attitudes to TJ are determined by a combination of individual, family and context-related (i.e. regional) factors. Over the following pages, we outline the theoretical significance of each of these factors, and the different mechanisms through which they are likely to have an impact on attitudes towards TJ. Individual Factors Individual characteristics are essential in explaining variation in political views; the list of relevant individual-level factors explaining variation in attitudes towards TJ is potentially endless. Therefore, we concentrate only on those we deem most relevant theoretically: The respondent’s age is an obvious factor in explaining differences in political views. With regard to TJ on past events, one would expect older people to be more   7 reluctant to support reparation policies because of their personal proximity to traumatic events. The mechanism driving this is fear, which might be operating more or less specifically: on the one hand, people may have a specific fear of reprisal from those who would be negatively affected by these policies (i.e. ex-victimizers);9 on the other hand, people may have a more general fear of a return of the conflict or the authoritarian regime (Nalepa 2007). While it could be argued that direct memories of traumatic events could also be stimulating a desire for reparations, we expect risk-aversion to prevail among those who witnessed the civil conflict or the ancien régime.10 Furthermore, with regard to the specific fear of reprisal, we can expect it to have a differential impact on TJ preferences depending on contextual factors such as the size of the locality where the individual lives: in larger municipalities, anonymity is greater than in smaller towns; in smaller settings, politics is more personal, and people are more likely to feel that reparation policies may have specific (i.e. negative) consequences for their own safety. The way individuals evaluate TJ measures should be clearly determined by their ability to understand not only the past in general, but also key historical events. Education is probably the single most important individual characteristic accounting for differentials in the extent to which individuals are able to do so, yet it may not be the only one: interest in politics might also play a role in their ability to evaluate these policies. For obvious reasons, individuals may have different views about TJ depending on their self-placement on the ideological axis. The direction of the effect will depend on the country’s history, including the trajectory of its political parties.11 Finally, religiosity and/or ethnicity are other individual characteristics to be considered insofar as victimization affects religious and/or ethnic groups unevenly.   8 Socialization and Family Factors The traditional focus of sociologists on the impact of family views and values in the formation of individual perceptions about life is reasonably intuitive. The literature on intergenerational transmission of political views underwent rapid growth in the seventies when Styskal and Sullivan (1975: 516-7) concluded: “Parents - the most trusted and revered of individuals in a person's early years - are the single most important force in transmitting party identification […] that choice of party, the substantive meaning of the party for the individual and the individual's orientation toward issues are more the products of loyalties derived from parents early in one's life, when cognitive processes are relatively underdeveloped, than the result of reflective decisions about alternatives in the political arena.” Indeed, despite the popular belief that during adolescence children will turn away from their parents in search of alternative guidance for value orientation, most empirical research reveals a striking concordance between the worldviews of parents and those of their (adult) children (Acock and Bengtson, 1980; Beck and Jennings, 1991; Dalhouse and Frideres, 1996; Jennings and Niemi, 1974; 1981; Jennings, Stoker and Bowers, 2009; Miller and Glass, 1989). Thus, individuals are expected to favor TJ policies to the extent that their parents do so. Moreover, we might argue that individuals will favor TJ policies if they adopt the condition of “victim” from their ancestors. Psychological effects of violence and other forms of victimization have been widely studied in the academic literature on conflict (e.g. the well-known “Post Traumatic Stress Disorder” or PTSD). However, the specific effects of traumatic experiences on individuals’ identities and behavior have generally been overlooked (Balcells, 2007), partly due to a lack of appropriate data for conducting empirical analyses. Although the recent development of surveys and experiments in postwar settings has prompted the development of empirical studies tackling these issues, the evidence is still quite fragmented and refers mainly to the short-term effects of   9 traumatic events (e.g. Bellows and Miguel, 2008). Neither do we find a much better state of the art in the study of individual experiences of dictatorships, and their subsequent preferences and opinions, both during and after democratization processes. This literature has usually focused on the role of political activists or highly committed individuals (Maravall, 1978; Ferreira, 1999), with only some recent developments concerning rank and file individuals (Wittenberg, 2006). Thus, the existing literature cannot provide an answer to the question of whether victimization generates long-term consequences on attitudes towards TJ measures. Nevertheless, it can be argued that, given the positive impact of personal victimization on support for reparation policies on a short-term basis (Nalepa, 2007; Gibson, 2002, 2004a, 2004b, 2007; Biro et al. 2004), victimizing experiences of family ancestors should also lead to favorable attitudes regarding reparation policies. The mechanism leading towards an intergenerational transmission of these attitudes should be the same as that which explains intergenerational transmission of political identities. In short, we can formulate the conjecture that victimization is a condition that is transmitted to descendants through socialization processes. Contextual Factors The literature has nevertheless found that the family is not the only socialization source for individuals: adult re-socialization experiences (both individual -partner, friends- and contextual) can erode the primary socialization effects of the parents. Thus, the broader context in which the individual lives, works and relates to other people can also have an influence on attitudes towards policies. Contextual factors can be varied and complex, as are the mechanisms through which they operate; a clear contextual variable, albeit not the only one, is the individual’s political community, e.g. the locality or the region. Within the community, the individual interacts according to a particular   10 set of cultural repertoires and discourses, and there is peer-reinforcement of these discourses. Irrespective of individual and family factors, if the citizens of a particular region or locality perceive that they have been distinctively victimized, we may think that they will hold more favorable attitudes towards TJ policies than elsewhere. [Figure 1 about here] Figure 1 summarizes the combination of factors which, according to our framework, should have an impact on individual preferences for TJ, and which should explain variations in these preferences among individuals. While depicted as independently affecting preferences, these factors may also be intermingled: for instance, socialization within the family can be affected by contextual factors (i.e. socialization and transmission of victimization within families may vary across regions). However, given the endless list of connections that could be drawn, and the impossibility of generating clear-cut observable implications for each of these interactions, we treat them as independent factors.12 4. Empirical Test In this section we will verify the explanatory power of each of the factors indicated above by examining data from the aforementioned CIS survey, which sampled 2,936 respondents throughout the country and is representative of the over-18 Spanish population.13 Conducted over a 10-day period through face-to-face interviews lasting around 30 minutes, this monographic survey on “historical memory” included 70 questions about historical and political knowledge, political attitudes and behavior, and socio-demographic characteristics. Following a common practice in the literature, we operationalized support for three different types of TJ measures with different survey questions:   11 1) For attitudes to the creation of a truth commission to inquire into past abuses: “From your point of view, should an investigation commission (independent from the government) be created in order to clarify human rights violations that took place under Francoism?”14 2) For attitudes towards trials to judge those responsible for past human rights violations: “Should the authorities that violated human rights under Francoism be brought to trial/judged?”15 3) For attitudes towards symbolic reparations, we used responses (agree/disagree) to the following statement: “Symbols that pay tribute to Franco and Francoism should be withdrawn from public spaces.” 16 To test our hypotheses, we include three subsets of independent and control variables in a set of step-wise binary and ordinal logistic regressions. We include a first set of independent variables measuring individual characteristics: (1) Age: we expect older respondents to be more reluctant to support TJ measures; we also expect to find some sort of interaction between age and the size of the respondent’s locality due to the anonymity provided by large localities.17 (2) Interest in politics:18 we expect exposure to the public debate concerning the “Law of Historical Memory” to promote clear-cut positions on the issue. We include this variable as a control.19 (3) Education:20 education increases the individual’s sophistication and thus her ability to formulate her own views about past events. (4) Religiosity:21 the religious division was a significant one in the context of the Spanish Civil War and the dictatorship -on the one hand, members of the clergy were victims of leftist violence during the conflict; and on the other, the Catholic Church sided with Franco during the Civil War and the dictatorship. Thus, we expect religiosity to have a negative impact on support for TJ measures.22 (5)   12 Ideology:23 we expect a clear-cut negative effect of right-wing ideology on support for TJ policies. We include a second set of variables proxying family characteristics and socialization: (1) Family Identity during the Civil War:24 those whose family identified with the Nationalists during the Civil War should be more negative towards TJ policies, and vice-versa. (2) Family talked about politics:25 this variable is included to control for the extent to which politics being discussed at home may influence the intergenerational transmission of identities and victimization. (3) Father’s ideology: this variable captures the parents’ ideology: 26 we expect a negative impact of right-wing parent ideology on support for TJ. (4) Family/Individual Victimization: we take into account victimization both by the Francoist side in the Civil War and by the Francoist dictatorship.27 The two variables included in the regressions are: (4.a) Victimization during the Civil War: dummy with value 1 if the respondent argues that she or a member of her family was victimized by the Francoist side during the Civil War, and value 0 if not.28 (4.b) Victimization during the dictatorship: dummy with value 1 if the respondent argues that she or any member of the family was victimized by the Francoist dictatorship, and value 0 if not.29 We expect people whose ancestors (or who themselves) have been victimized to be more supportive of TJ.30 Victimization experiences should also have a differential effect depending on the individual’s age: the older the person is, the more intensely she will feel the victimizing experience; we will test this with an interaction term in the regression models. A final set of variables is intended to measure contextual factors. As previously stated, we focus on the regional level. The Francoist dictatorship strongly repressed cultural and linguistic minorities within Spain; this led to a collective sense of victimization among these groups, which has persisted through time. Given that our   13 survey has representative sub-samples for the Basque Country and Catalonia31 -two territories with the most distinguishable ethnic identities and strongest sense of collective victimization in Spain- we can easily incorporate a regional dummy variable into our regressions. In this respect, we expect the (1) Basque Country and (2) Catalonia dummies to have a positive effect on support for all TJ measures. Figures 2-4 show the distribution of the responses in the different items constituting our three dependent variables: the creation of a truth commission to investigate human rights violations under Francoism (Truth Commissions), the organization of trials to judge those responsible for human rights violations during Francoism (Trials), and the withdrawal from public spaces of symbols paying tribute to Franco and Francoism (Symbols). [Figures 2-4 about here] These graphs indicate that, except in the first case (truth commissions), Spaniards are overtly supportive of TJ policies. This is interesting, as the strong resistance to the “Law of Historical Memory” displayed by the main right-wing party in Spain (Partido Popular) and the conservative mass media would lead us to expect a greater degree of opposition to these policies. We also observe that people are more prone to agreeing to symbolic reparations (withdrawal of symbols) than to the other two TJ measures (truth commission, trials). This is rather intuitive and consistent with patterns observed in other cases, e.g. the American South (Sheridan, 2009). Additionally, trials receive more support than truth commissions, and truth commissions elicit a greater number of hesitant answers than the other policies.32 Table 1 shows the results of the first logistic regression analyses for the dependent variable Commissions, indicating the likelihood of supporting this particular reparatory measure.33 Model 0 incorporates an interaction term between Age and Size   14 of locality, which should allow us to capture the varying effect of Age conditional on the degree of anonymity in which individuals live. We do not include this interaction in the remaining models. Model 1 includes only individual factors, Models 2-3 add socialization and family factors, Model 4 includes an interaction between age and victimization, and Model 5 completes the specification with context-related variables. [Table 1 about here] Model 0 in Table 1 reveals an interesting result that confirms our expectations regarding the interaction between respondent’s Age and Size of locality: the main effect of age is negative, i.e. the older the respondent, the less likely she is to accept the creation of commissions. However, this main effect changes depending on whether the individual lives in a small town or a large city: older people in large cities are less reluctant to support the creation of commissions than those in small towns (regardless of age, the smaller the town, the more reluctant an individual will be). Again, this can be explained by the fear of negative reactions in smaller (and less anonymous) locations. This interactive effect disappears when controlling for other individual level variables, especially self-placement on the left-right scale and religiosity.  Our basic expectations about individual level variables are confirmed by Model 1. The effect of Age is again negative and statistically significant; Religiosity and Ideology are both negatively associated with the likelihood of accepting commissions, which means the more religious and more right-wing the person is, the more reluctant she is to support this measure. It is somewhat striking that Education and Interest in politics are not statistically significant. This could be due to the fact that the TJ debate, far from being a transversal ideology-free debate, is intensively politicized. Model 2 tests the impact of family-level ideology factors. It suggests that individuals whose families sided with the Francoists during the Civil War are   15 significantly less prone to accept commissions than other individuals. There are no differences in the propensity of individuals whose families were on the Republican side and those whose families were divided and fought on both sides. Thus, with regard to their family histories, individuals are significantly less likely to accept commissions if they come from a homogeneous Nationalist background; having had at least part of one’s family on the Republican side increases acceptance of this measure. The ideology of the respondent’s father has no impact on the dependent variable, although the sign of this estimate is as predicted (i.e. negative). An interesting result drawn from this model is that individuals are more likely to support the creation of commissions when the family used to talk about politics. This could be taken as evidence confirming the importance of socialization in the formation of attitudes towards TJ. Interestingly, this effect decreases after controlling for the victimization variables. Model 3 tests the family victimization hypotheses. Interestingly, victimization does not appear to be a homogeneous experience. Being a victim of the Francoist army in the Civil War has no impact on our dependent variable. However, individuals reporting experiences of victimization during Francoism are more likely to accept commissions than others; the magnitude of this effect is quite important and it is highly statistically significant. Therefore, more recent victimization (i.e. during the dictatorship) appears to be more relevant than victimization during the Civil War. This result is consistent with the fact that the truth commissions would focus on human rights violations committed under the dictatorship, and not during the Civil War. We have tested for the interactive hypotheses between reported victimization and age (model 4). Our expectation was that the impact of victimization would decrease among younger respondents, yet we cannot fully confirm this conjecture as this   16 interaction is not statistically significant (although it has a positive sign). Thus, victimization seems to be strongly transmitted to new generations: its impact, which is positive and highly statistically significant, does not change with the respondents’ age. Note also that the main effect of Age scarcely changes and remains negative in the victimization models; this means that, for those who report past experiences of family victimization, support for TJ is independent of their age. Finally, Model 5 indicates that Catalan respondents do not differ from those from other regions in their propensity to accept commissions, whereas the Basques are generally more likely to support this sort of reparation. [Table 2 about here] Table 2 depicts the results for the dependent variable Trials. In this case, Model 0 cannot fully confirm our hypothesis regarding the differential effect of age conditional on town size: the interaction is not statistically significant. Model 1 is fairly consistent with its equivalent in Table 1; it confirms the relevance of individual-level explanatory variables: Ideology, Religiosity, and Education (this was not statistically significant in Table 1). More educated people are less supportive of TJ. Model 2 reveals additional differences with respect to what we observed in Table 1: coming from a family who sided with the Republicans during the Civil War increases the likelihood of supporting trials. And the opposite is also true: respondents whose families sided with the Francoists are significantly less supportive of trials. Model 3 rejects a general impact of victimization on the acceptance of past perpetrators being brought to trial: indeed, none of the victimization variables is significant. However, Model 4 reveals a significant interaction between age and reported victimization by the Franco regime: older respondents reporting victimization are significantly more in favor of this measure than the rest of the sample. Older   17 respondents who report no victimization clearly reject holding trials, and younger people reporting victimization also oppose this measure, which indicates that victimization experiences lead to different attitudes towards reparatory measures depending on the individual’s age. In model 5, both regional dummies are statistically significant. Respondents in the Basque Country and Catalonia are more likely to accept the holding of trials than respondents in other territories, and this effect is greater in the former territory than in the latter. [Table 3 about here] Table 3 tests the determinants of attitudes towards symbolic reparation measures; the dependent variable measures approval of the withdrawal of symbols of Francoism. The first model (Model 0) suggests -as in Table 1- that even though older respondents are generally more reluctant to support this symbolic reparation, those living in larger urban areas are less likely to be so. Furthermore, as in Table 1, the only significant socio-demographic variables are -in addition to respondent’s age- Ideology and Religiosity. In this case, the position of the respondents appears to be heavily dependent on family variables (Model 2). Indeed: there is an almost linear association between family leanings in the civil conflict and respondent attitudes regarding this measure: whenever the respondent recalls a Francoist past in her family, her likelihood of accepting this form of symbolic reparation significantly decreases, as compared to those who claim to have roots on both sides. And when the individual comes from a family that fought on the Republican side, she is more likely to accept this reparation, as compared to those whose relatives were divided on both sides. Victimization (Model 3) is more significantly related to our dependent variable than in the previous models (Tables 1 and 2). Both estimates of victimization (victimization by of Francoism and bythe Nationalist side during the Civil War) are significant here. Interestingly, the   18 interaction between victimization and respondent’s age (Model 4) is not significant, implying that this effect is equally important among respondents of all ages. Our final model (Model 5) reconfirms the Basque and Catalan specificity; this regional effect is again stronger in the former region than in the latter.34 A caveat to our empirical results is that the observed effects of victimization on attitudes towards TJ are an artifact of an endogenous relationship between reported victimization and ideology. It could be that those identified with the left are more prone to report past victimization experiences than those who identified with the right. A graphic inspection of the distribution of these two sub-samples along the ideological axis allows us to observe that these two subsamples have almost undistinguishable distributions. [Figure 5 about here] However, a Kolmogorov-Smirnov test performed on the distribution along the ideological axis (i.e. left-right) of the sub-samples of victimized/non-victimized individuals suggests that these samples are significantly different, non-victims being located further to the right than non-victims (Table 4). This indicates that endogeneity cannot be completely discarded. [Table 4 about here] Unfortunately, we do not have an instrumental variable for ‘victimization’, or an experimental design, which would allow for a better identification strategy. We nevertheless believe that the fact that we have controlled for the effect of each of these variables (i.e. ideology and victimization) on the other by including them in the same regression model should give us some degree of methodological comfort.   19 To summarize, the general patterns identified in these results above are as follows: respondent’s ideology and religiosity are decisive determinants of support, more conservative and religious people being the most reluctant towards TJ policies. The fact that the Catholic Church, in contrast to what happened in countries like Argentina, has never shown any regret for its support of Francoism (both during the Civil War and the dictatorship), may help to explain why, still today, religiosity is negatively associated with support for TJ measures. The effect of other individual-level variables is modest. Age is a relevant predictor of support, older respondents being less likely to support TJ. This variable appears to have a differential impact across town of residence; the effect of being older is stronger (more negative) in smaller towns, which tallies with the observed resistance to TJ policies in small villages (Aguilar 2008b). Education is only significant in one of our models although, interestingly enough, its coefficient has a negative sign in all models of the three tables. Regarding the impact of family socialization, we find that, 70 years after the Civil War and more than 30 years after the dictatorship, reported victimization -suffered by the respondent or their relatives- is crucial in explaining current attitudes towards TJ. This conclusion suggests that more attention should be paid to personal and family experiences in the formation of political views and attitudes, especially if they are traumatic. In South Africa, Backer (2006) has found significant differences between direct victims of the Apartheid and the rest of the population regarding satisfaction with the TRC. In Rwanda, a survey study of the ICTJ has also found that “personal experiences shaped respondents’ attitudes” (referred in Thoms et al. 2008: 79). In general, the impact of victimization is unrelated to the respondent’s age, which confirms the decisive importance of intergenerational transmission of views about traumatic events.35 The only exception to this is the significant effect of the age   20 parameter on support for trials (Table 2); one explanation could be that reparatory aspects of justice are more likely to be transmitted across generations than retributive ones. This might also be indicative that the revenge impulse tends to fade over time, whereas the need to see the victims properly redressed may be more easily and frequently maintained. Finally, we have found that contextual factors are relevant in explaining attitudes towards TJ policies. In this paper we have focused on regional-level factors, which are intuitively very relevant in the Spanish case, with the Catalan and Basque minorities. 36 However, differences could also occur at other levels of aggregation. For example, Arjona (2009) has emphasized the importance of the municipal level for reparation policies in Colombia. The significance of these contextual differences will depend not only on the existence of different victimizing experiences, but also on a certain degree of collective self-awareness and mechanisms for its reproduction. 5. Conclusions Frequently starting from normative rather than empirically demonstrated assumptions, the TJ literature has traditionally focused on the different political strategies developed by political actors either to promote or to oppose institutional arrangements aimed either at redressing victims or at bringing perpetrators to justice. In doing so, there has been a tendency to disregard public opinion towards TJ policies. This is unfortunate, as the use of surveys gives us “a better sense of how pro- and anti- TJ constituencies emerge” (Thoms, 2008: 47; 78). This paper, which has sought to explain determinants of popular attitudes towards TJ in contemporary Spain, represents a contribution to the specialized literature on the topic. We have analyzed TJ as disaggregated in different types of measures, which can either be complementary or alternative to each other. We have observed that   21 variation in support for TJ interventions issues from a combination of individual and family-level (socialization) variables. In general terms, those who are more likely to support these measures are people who are closer to the left, younger, and non-religious, but also people whose families sided with the Republicans during the Civil War and/or were victimized during the dictatorship. We have also identified some contextual (regional) differences, which make the likelihood of supporting TJ greater in those parts of the country where strong and differentiated ethnic or national identities prevail. While the findings related to ideology, religiosity, age or town size may be dependent on the specificities of Spain (even though some could be relevant in other cases), a lesson that transcends this case is that policies that are perceived as being less aggressive, such as withdrawing symbols of the past (something that does not entail digging into the past to identify human rights violations and perpetrators), are more widely supported by the citizenry. In contrast, measures perceived as more risky (i.e. creation of truth commissions and holding of trials) are less widely supported by citizens. The importance of differentiating between the more moderate and the more radical instruments, and even attempts to create an ordered scale or a “spectrum” of TJ policies, has started to be considered in the literature (Payne et al., 2008; Grodsky, 2009). In other words, TJ measures do not appear to be reducible to a single dimension; and, depending on their nature, different interventions are likely to generate different levels of popular support. The results illustrate the long-term relevance of victimization and socialization on political identities. On the one hand, individuals do not seem to be forgetful of their history, i.e. the mere passage of time does not necessarily contribute to oblivion. In Spain, the lack of appropriate TJ measures may have prevented victims and their relatives from leaving the past behind. On the other hand, the condition of victim, which   22 may be more or less specific (i.e. relating to the family or the political community), seems to travel from one generation to another and to have clear-cut political consequences. Interestingly, Carmil and Breznitz (1990) reached a similar conclusion in their research on the effect of the trauma derived from the Holocaust experience on both the survivors and their descendants. Indeed, even if in this paper we have focused on attitudes towards TJ policies, the effects of victimizing experiences are likely to be broader (e.g. on political identities) (Balcells, 2007; Wood, 2008). To conclude, our work underscores the importance of micro-level data for the study of TJ, which can reveal unpredicted empirical patterns. For example, at the mere descriptive level, our study has clarified the views of Spaniards regarding TJ issues. Our data demonstrate that, contrary to what has been commonly assumed, Spaniards are reasonably supportive of the application of TJ policies.37 In fact, the data indicates that the average Spanish citizen would have endorsed a more ambitious legal application of TJ principles than that provided for in the 2007 “Law of Historical Memory”.   23 References Acock, A. & Bengtson, V. L. (1980). Socialization and Attribution: Actual versus Perceived Similarity among Parents and Youth. Journal of Marriage and the Family, 42, 501-515. Aguilar, P. (2002). Memory and Amnesia: The Role of the Spanish Civil War in the Transition to Democracy. Oxford & NY: Berghahn Books. Aguilar, P. (2008a). Transitional or Post-Transitional Justice? Recent Developments in the Spanish Case. South European Society & Politics 13(4), 417-433. Aguilar, P. (2008b). Políticas de la memoria y memorias de la política. Madrid: Alianza Editorial. Arjona, A. (2009). One national war, multiple local orders: an inquiry into the unit of analysis of war and post-war interventions. In Law in Peace Negotiations, edited by M. Bergsmo and P. Kalmanovitz. Oslo: PRIO. Balcells, L. (2007). The Effects of Wars on Political Identities: Ideological Change and Continuity after the Spanish Civil War (1936–39). Paper presented at the Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association, Chicago, IL. Barahona de Brito, A., González-Enríquez, C., & Aguilar, P. (Eds.) (2001). The Politics of Memory. Transitional Justice in Democratizing Societies. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Backer, D. (2003). Civil Society and Transitional Justice: Possibilities, Patterns and Prospects. Journal of Human Rights 2, 297-313. Beck, P. A., & Jennings, M.K. (1991). Family Traditions, Political Periods, and the Development of Partisan Orientations. The Journal of Politics, 53(3), 742-763. Bellows, J. & E. Miguel (2008) War and Collective Action in Sierra Leone. Working Paper, University of California, Berkeley.   24 Biro, Miklos et al. (2004). Attitudes toward Justice and Social Reconstruction in Bosnia and Herzegovina and Croatia. In E. Strover, & H. M. Weinstein (Eds.) My Neighbor, My Enemy. Justice and Community in the Aftermath of Mass Atrocity (pp. 183-205). Cambridge, N.Y.: Cambridge University Press. Carmil, D., & Breznitz, S. (1990). Personal Trauma and World View –Are Extremely Stressful Experiences Related to Political Attitudes, Religious Beliefs, and Future Orientation? Journal of Traumatic Stress, 4 (3), 393-405. Dalhouse, M., & Frideres, J.S. (1996). Intergenerational Congruency: The Role of the Family in Political Attitudes of Youth. Journal of Family Issues, 17, 227- 248. David, R. & Choi, S.Y. (2006). Forgiveness and Transitional Justice in the Czech Republic. The Journal of Conflict Resolution, 50(3), 339-367. Davis, M. (2005). Is Spain Recovering its Memory? Breaking the Pacto del Olvido. Human Rights Quarterly, 27 (3), 858–880. De Greiff, Pablo (not dated). Theorizing Transitional Justice. Unpublished paper. Elster, J. (1998). Coming to Terms with the Past. A Framework for the Study of Justice in the Transition to Democracy. Archives Européennes de Sociologie, XXXIX(1), 7-48. Elster, J. (2004). Closing the Books. Transitional Justice in Historical Perspective. NY: Cambridge University Press. Elster, J. (2006). (Ed.) Retribution and Reparation in the Transition to Democracy. NY: Cambridge University Press. Espinoza Cuevas, V., Ortiz Rojas, M.L., & Rojas Baeza, P. (2003). Comisiones de la verdad. ¿Un camino incierto? Chile: Corporación de Promoción y Defensa de los Derechos del Pueblo.   25 Ferreira, E. F. (1999). Mujeres, memoria e identidad política. Historia, Antropología y Fuente Oral 21, 53-66. Gibson, J. L. (2002). Truth, Justice, and Reconciliation: Judging the Fairness of Amnesty in South Africa. American Journal of Political Science, 46(3), 540-556. Gibson, J. L. (2004a). Does Truth Lead to Reconciliation? Testing the Causal Assumptions of the South African Truth and Reconciliation Process. American Journal of Political Science, 48(2), 201-217. Gibson, J. L. (2004b). Overcoming Apartheid: Can Truth Reconcile a Divided Nation? NY: Russell Sage Foundation. Gibson, J. L. (2007). “Truth” and “Reconciliation” as Social Indicators. Social Indicators Research, 81, 257-281. Grodsky, B. (2008). Weighing the Costs of Accountability: The Role of Institutional Incentives in Pursuing Transitional Justice. Journal of Human Rights, 7, 353-375. Grodsky, B. (2009). Re-Ordering Justice: Towards A New Methodological Approach to Studying Transitional Justice. Journal of Peace Research, 46(6), 1-19. ICTJ. (May 2004). Iraqi Voices: Attitudes toward Transitional Justice and Social Reconstruction. ICTJ. (August 2008). Living with Fear: A Population-based Survey on Attitudes about Peace, Justice and Social Reconstruction in Eastern Democratic Republic of Congo. Jennings, M.K. & Niemi, R. G. (1974). The Political Character of Adolescence. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Jennings, M.K. & Niemi, R.G. (1981). Generations and Politics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.   26 Jennings, M.K., Stoker, J. & Bowers, J. (2009). Politics across Generations: Family Transmission Reexamined. The Journal of Politics 71(3), 782-799. Juliá, S. (ed.) (2004). Víctimas de la Guerra Civil. Madrid: Temas de Hoy. Kritz, N. J. (Ed.) (1995). Transitional Justice: How Emerging Democracies Reckon with Former Regimes. Washington D.C.: United States Institute of Peace Press. Koonings, K., & Kruijt, D. (Ed). (1999). Societies of Fear: the Legacy of Civil War, Violence and Terror in Latin America. London: Zed Books. Longman, T., et al. (2004). Connecting Justice to Human Experience: Attitudes Toward Accountability and Reconciliation in Rwanda, in E. Strover & H. M. Weinstein (Eds.) My Neighbor, My Enemy. Justice and Community in the Aftermath of Mass Atrocity, (pp.206- 225). Cambridge, N.Y.: Cambridge University Press. Maravall, J. M. (1978). Dictatorship and Political Dissent. Workers and Students in Franco’s Spain. London: Tavistock. Martin Beristain, C. (2008). Diálogos sobre la reparación. Experiencias en el sistema interamericano de derechos humanos. Costa Rica: Instituto Interamericano de Derechos Humanos. McAdams, J. A. (Ed.) (1997). Transitional Justice and the Rule of Law in New Democracies. Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press. Miller, R.B., & Glass, J. 1989. Parent-Child Attitude Similarity across the Life Course. Journal of Marriage and the Family, 51, 991-997. Montero, J. R., Calvo, K., & Martínez, A. (2008). El voto religioso en España y Portugal. Revista Internacional de Sociología, 51, 19-54 Nalepa, M. (2007). Procedural Fairness and Demand for Transitional Justice: Evidence from East Central Europe. Paper presented at the Annual Meeting of the Midwest Political Science Association, Chicago, IL.   27 Nalepa, M. (2008). To Punish the Guilty and Protect the Innocent. Comparing Truth Revelation Procedures. Journal of Theoretical Politics, 2(20), 221-245. Nalepa, M. (2010). Skeletons in the Closet: Transitional Justice in Post- Communist Europe. NY: Cambridge University Press (forthcoming). Payne, Leigh et al. (2008). Does Transitional Justice Work? Presented at the International Studies Association Convention, San Francisco. Sheridan, E. (2009). Transitional Justice and the American South. Presented at the Annual Meeting of the Midwest Political Science Association Meeting, Chicago, IL. Skaar, E. (1999). Truth Commissions, Trials or Nothing. Third World Quarterly, 20(6), 1109-1128. Strover, E., & Weinstein, H.M. (Eds.) (2004). My Neighbor, My Enemy. Justice and Community in the Aftermath of Mass Atrocity. Cambridge, N.Y.: Cambridge University Press. Styskal, R. A., & Sullivan, H. J. (1975). Intergenerational Continuity and Congruence on Political Values. Political Research Quarterly, 28, 516-527. Taylor, G., Samii, C., & Mvukiyehe, E. (2006). Wartime and Post-Conflict Experiences in Burundi: An Individual Level Survey. Presented at September 2006 APSA Meeting, Philadelphia. Available at: http://www.columbia.edu/~cds81/burundisurvey Tedin, K. L. (1974). The Influence of Parents on the Political Attitudes of Adolescents. American Political Science Review, 68, 1579-92. Teitel, R. (2000). Transitional Justice. NY: Oxford University Press. Theidon, K. (2006). The Micropolitics of Reconciliation in Postwar Peru. Journal of Conflict Resolution, 50(3), 433-457.   28 Thoms, O., Ron, J., & Paris, R. (2008). The Effects of Transitional Justice Mechanisms, CIPS Working Paper, University of Ottawa. Wittenberg, J. (2006). Crucibles of Political Loyalty: Church Institutions and Electoral Continuity in Hungary. NY: Cambridge University Press. Wood, E. (2008). The Social Processes of Civil War: The Wartime Transformation of Social Networks. Annual Review of Political Science, 11, 539-61.   29 Tables and Figures Table 1. Logit Regressions: Creation of a truth commission for investigating human rights violations under Francoism Commissions M0 M1 M2 M3 M4 M5 Age effect Age -0.023*** -0.008** -0.006 -0.010*** -0.011*** -0.011*** (0.01) (0.00) (0.00) (0.00) (0.00) (0.00) Town size -0.144* -0.022 -0.025 -0.027 -0.027 -0.024 (0.08) (0.03) (0.03) (0.03) (0.03) (0.03) Town size*age 0.003* (0.00) Individual level Interest in politics 0.013 -0.027 -0.053 -0.052 -0.052 (0.06) (0.06) (0.07) (0.07) (0.07) Education -0.110 -0.112 -0.127 -0.126 -0.132 (0.09) (0.09) (0.09) (0.09) (0.09) Religiosity -0.175*** -0.151*** -0.130*** -0.129*** -0.133*** (0.04) (0.05) (0.05) (0.05) (0.05) Ideology -0.340*** -0.287*** -0.288*** -0.288*** -0.286*** (0.03) (0.04) (0.04) (0.04) (0.04) Socialization (1) Family on Francoist side in Civil War -0.382** (0.15) -0.268* (0.16) -0.266* (0.16) -0.264* (0.16) Family on Republican side in CW 0.075 0.005 0.003 -0.001 (0.13) (0.13) (0.13) (0.13) Family talked about politics 0.201*** 0.140*** 0.139** 0.137* (0.07) (0.07) (0.07) (0.07) Father’s ideology -0.026 -0.029 -0.029 -0.029 (0.03) (0.03) (0.03) (0.03) Victim of Francoism 0.839*** 0.700* 0.831*** (0.13) (0.36) (0.13) Victim of Francoists in the CW 0.029 (0.13) 0.030 (0.13) 0.034 (0.13) Age*victimization 0.003 (0.01) Regional differences (2) Catalonia -0.017 (0.14) Basque country 0.451* (0.27) Constant 1.200 2.679 2.160 2.331 2.360*** 2.326*** (0.35) (0.34) (0.37) (0.38) (0.39) (0.38) N 1704 1704 1704 1704 1704 1704 Chi2 20.33*** 208.84*** 229.89*** 275.177*** 275.349*** 278.20*** Akaike’s IC 2346.117 2163.602 2150.561 2109.274 2111.102 2110.250 Legend: * p<.1; ** p<.05; *** p<.01 (1) The reference category comprises those who said their family fought on both sides during the Civil War. (2) The reference category comprises all other Spaniards.   30 Table 2. Ordinal Logit Regressions: The authorities that violated human rights under Francoism should be brought to trial Trials M0 M1 M2 M3 M4 M5 Age effect Age -0.028*** -0.015*** -0.016*** -0.016*** -0.021*** -0.017*** (0.01) (0.00) (0.00) (0.00) (0.00) (0.00) Town size -0.092 0.030 0.029 0.029 0.027 0.030 (0.08) (0.03) (0.03) (0.03) (0.03) (0.03) Town size*age 0.003 (0.00) Individual level Interest in politics -0.007 -0.011 -0.013 -0.007 -0.008 (0.06) (0.06) (0.06) (0.06) (0.06) Education -0.144* -0.125 -0.127 -0.122 -0.137 (0.09) (0.09) (0.09) (0.09) (0.09) Religiosity -0.127*** -0.101** -0.100*** -0.093** -0.090** (0.04) (0.04) (0.04) (0.04) (0.04) Ideology -0.325*** -0.264*** -0.263*** -0.260*** -0.251*** (0.03) (0.04) (0.04) (0.04) (0.04) Socialization (1) Family on Francoist side in Civil War -0.249* -0.243* -0.230 -0.252* (0.14) (0.14) (0.14) (0.14) Family on Republican side in CW 0.363*** 0.357*** 0.343*** 0.297*** (0.13) (0.13) (0.13) (0.13) Family talked about politics 0.025 0.021 0.014 0.011 (0.07) (0.07) (0.07) (0.07) Father’s ideology -0.015 -0.014 -0.014 -0.016 (0.03) (0.03) (0.03) (0.03) Victim of Francoism 0.045 -0.732** 0.073 (0.12) (0.33) (0.12) Victim of Francoists in CW 0.012 0.027 0.002 (0.12) (0.12) (0.12) Age*victimization 0.017** (0.01) Regional Catalonia 0.558*** differences (2) (0.15) Basque country 0.969*** (0.28) Cut point 1 -1.981 -3.540 -3.146 -3.149 -3.343 -3.061 (0.35) (0.33) (0.36) (0.36) (0.37) (0.36) Cut point 2 -1.518 -3.032 -2.632 -2.636 -2.828 -2.540 (0.35) (0.33) (0.36) (0.36) (0.37) (0.36) N 1737 1737 1737 1737 1737 1737 Chi2 44.42*** 215.54*** 233.94*** 234.12*** 240.65*** 259.918*** Akaike’s IC 3129.685 2964.560 2954.169 2957.987 2953.453 2936.186 Legend: * p<.1; ** p<.05; *** p<.01 (1) The reference category comprises those who said their family fought on both sides during the Civil War. (2) The reference category comprises all other Spaniards.   31 Table 3. Ordinal Logit Regressions: Symbols paying tribute to Francoism should be withdrawn from public spaces Symbols M0 M1 M2 M3 M4 M5 Age effect Age -0.032*** 0.001 0.001 -0.001 -0.003 -0.003 (0.01) (0.00) (0.00) (0.00) (0.00) (0.00) Town size -0.284*** -0.023 -0.023 -0.025 -0.026 -0.024 (0.08) (0.03) (0.03) (0.03) (0.03) (0.03) Town size*age 0.006*** (0.00) Individual level Interest in politics 0.089 0.103 0.089 0.091 0.093 (0.06) (0.07) (0.07) (0.07) (0.07) Education -0.031 -0.014 -0.032 -0.031 -0.044 (0.09) (0.09) (0.09) (0.09) (0.09) Religiosity -0.250*** -0.220*** -0.209*** -0.208*** -0.203*** (0.04) (0.04) (0.04) (0.04) (0.04) Ideology -0.436*** -0.387*** -0.383*** -0.382*** -0.374*** (0.03) (0.04) (0.04) (0.04) (0.04) Socialization (1) Family in Francoist side in the Civil War -0.449*** -0.384*** -0.377** -0.386*** (0.14) (0.14) (0.14) (0.15) Family in Republican side in the Civil War 0.271** 0.183 0.178 0.121 (0.14) (0.14) (0.14) (0.14) Family talked about politics -0.007 -0.042 -0.044 -0.050 (0.07) (0.07) (0.07) (0.07) Father’s ideology 0.016 0.019 0.020 0.020 (0.03) (0.03) (0.03) (0.03) Victim of Francoism 0.366*** 0.107 0.384*** (0.13) (0.36) (0.14) Victim of Francoists in the Civil War 0.248* 0.253* 0.234* (0.13) (0.13) (0.13) Age*victimization 0.006 (0.01) Regional differences (2) (ref. is other) Catalonia 0.456*** (0.16) Basque country 1.464*** (0.36) Cut point 1 -2.666*** -3.803*** -3.365*** -3.410*** -3.463*** -3.347*** (0.35) (0.35) (0.38) (0.38) (0.38) (0.38) Cut point 2 -2.171*** -3.217*** -2.773*** -2.815*** -2.867*** -2.743*** (0.35) (0.34) (0.37) (0.37) (0.38) (0.38) N 1807 1807 1807 1807 1807 1807 Chi2 24.772*** 333.980*** 351.872*** 366.238*** 366.817*** 395.031*** Akaike’s IC 3082.796 2779.588 2769.696 2759.330 2760.750 2734.537 Legend: * p<.1; ** p<.05; *** p<.01 (1) The reference category comprises those who said their family fought on both sides during the Civil War. (2) The reference category comprises all other Spaniards.   32    Table 4. Two-sample Kolmogorov-Smirnov test for equality of distribution functions Smaller group D P.value Non-victims 0 1.00 Victims -0.12 0.00 Combined K-S 0.12 0.00   33 Figure 1. Determinants of TJ policies Attitudes towards TJ measures Individual factors Socialization Parental ideology Family victimization Contextual factors   34 Figure 2. Support for the creation of a truth commission to investigate human rights violations under Francoism   35 Figure 3- Support for trials against authorities that violated human rights under Francoism   36 Figure 4. Support for the withdrawal of monuments paying tribute to Francoism   37 Figure 5. Ideology self-placement for victims and non-victims 0 5 10 15 20 25 30 Extreme left 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 Extreme right No victimization  reported Victimization  reported D en si ty ( % o f re sp o n d en ts )   38 Appendix Descriptive statistics Variable name N Mean Std. Dev. Min Max Trials 2,525 2.36 0.87 1 3 Symbols 2,667 2.49 0.81 1 3 Monuments 2,617 2.50 0.80 1 3 Commissions 2,426 0.52 0.49 0 1 Age 2,936 47.17 18.15 18 99 Town size 2,936 3.87 1.65 1 7 Interest in politics 2,919 2.08 0.88 1 4 Education 2,929 1.91 0.70 1 3 Religiosity 2,868 2.50 1.35 1 6 Ideology 2,435 4.39 1.74 1 10 Victim of Francoism 2,936 0.24 0.42 0 1 Victim of Francoists in CW 2,936 0.31 0.46 0 1 Family on Francoist side in CW 2,936 0.15 0.36 0 1 Family on Republican side in CW 2,936 0.32 0.46 0 1 Family talked about politics 2,854 1.91 0.82 1 4 Father’s ideology 2,103 4.82 2.21 1 10 Catalonia 2,936 0.23 0.42 0 1 Basque country 2,936 0.23 0.42 0 1     39                                                              Endnotes 1 The first category includes: trials; annulment of auto-amnesties approved by officials of the previous regime; legislation expropriating illegitimately acquired assets of former authoritarian parties; lustration or purging of individuals actively involved with the authoritarian regime. Reparation ranges from various forms of material compensatory policies (e.g. restitution of confiscated property rights, or provision of pensions to the victims or their families) to symbolic measures (e.g. memorials to the victims, or official apologies). Truth revelation procedures normally entail the creation of commissions and/or the declassification of secret police archives. 2 See, among others, Kritz (1995); McAdams (1997); Teitel (2000); Barahona de Brito et al. (2001); Elster (1998; 2004; 2006); Nalepa (2008; 2010); De Greiff (not dated). 3 While the latter caveat applies to any policy, it is particularly relevant in the case of TJ for a number of reasons: firstly, civil society is likely to be weakened in the aftermath of an authoritarian experience and/or a violent conflict, and organizational resources to lobby for TJ are likely to be scarce. Secondly, even if there is an underlying desire for these type of measures in society, people are not likely to openly request them for fear of political destabilization, residual power of the repressive actors, and the like. Finally, pressures exerted by a number of social actors aimed at advancing TJ may simply be representative of a few groups with highly intense preferences (i.e. victims and their relatives), and not of the society in general. 4 A notable exception is Gibson’s (2002; 2004a; 2004b) research in South Africa. Through representative surveys at national level, his research has focused on the reconciliatory effects of the Truth and Reconciliation Commission (TRC), as well as on the social perception of justice derived from this institution. Nalepa (2008; 2010) has   40                                                                                                                                                                                also implemented representative surveys in Hungary, Poland and Czech Republic on matters related to TJ policies. Other studies based on survey research are listed in Thoms et. al. (2008: 78-85). 5 The estimated death toll during the Civil War is 800,000, of which around 122,000 are estimated to be civilian victims of intentional lethal violence –of these, 84,095 were victims of Francoist violence, and 37,843 were victims of Leftist violence (Juliá 2004). 6 Aguilar (2008a) argues that a crucial factor explaining the resurgence of this debate is the arrival in the public sphere of the “grandchildren of the war”, who were free from the fears and guilt of their parents. Davis (2005: 868) has pointed to the importance of Pinochet’s arrest in London -after an initiative by the Spanish judge Baltasar Garzón- in understanding these changes. 7 Official State Gazette nº 310, of 27th December 2007, p.53410. It will be referred to in this article as the “Law of Historical Memory”, the name it has been given in the mass media. 8 See, for example, Nalepa (2007) for Poland, the Czech Republic and Hungary; David and Choi (2006) for the Czech Republic; Theidon (2006) for Peru; Gibson (2002, 2004a, 2004b, 2007) for South Africa; Biro et al. (2004) for Bosnia and Herzegovina and Croatia. 9 The effect of the perceived threat from members linked to the authoritarian regime is studied by Nalepa (2007), who finds it to be a significant predictor of attitudes towards lustration in Poland, Czech Republic and Hungary. This factor was also found to be significant in South Africa (Gibson, 2004b). 10 On trauma and fear arising from repression in authoritarian regimes, see Koonings and Kruijt (1999).   41                                                                                                                                                                                11 In Spain, leftist ideology would be expected to be associated with support for TJ policies. The opposite would apply in other contexts (i.e. post-Communist settings). 12 Nonetheless, we will empirically explore a different set of interactions. 13 The Basque Country and Catalonia are over-represented, with 699 and 683 respondents, respectively. In our analyses, we take into account this over-representation so that the results are perfectly representative of the whole country. 14 The response options are 1 = Yes; 2 = No; 3 = Doesn’t Know; 4 = Doesn’t Answer; we built a dummy variable with values 1 = Yes; 0 = No. 15 Responses are measured on a scale from 1 to 3 where 1 = “Completely disagree”; 3 = “Completely agree”; 2 = “Neither agree nor disagree.” 16 The same scale as in 2 applies. 17 Town size is entered as an ordinal variable (on a scale 1-7) following the usual coding in CIS surveys. The categories are: 1 = 2,000 or fewer inhabitants; 2 = between 2,001 and 10,000; 3 = between 10,001 and 50,000; 4 = between 50,001 and 100,000; 5 = between 100,001 and 400,000; 6 = between 400,001 and 1,000,000; 7 = more than 1,000,000. 18 “Could you tell me if you are interested in politics in general?” Possible responses are 4 = Very much; 3 = Quite a lot; 2 = A little; 1 = Not at all. 19 Indeed, education and interest in politics are two mandatory controls in our estimation, since individuals scoring higher in one or both are much less likely to give a “does not know” type of answer. Adding these controls helps to avoid sample bias. 20 The variable has the values 1 for primary education or less; 2 for secondary education; 3 for university degree.   42                                                                                                                                                                                21 This is a scalar variable that goes from 1 to 6, where 1 is non-religious (i.e. the respondent identifies herself as atheist or non-religious) and 6 highly religious (i.e. the respondent says that she goes to mass several days a week). 22 While the impact of religion on Spanish politics is not as strong as it used to be, it remains a significant factor explaining voting and electoral competition (Montero et al., 2008). 23 This variable measures the self-reported position on the left-right scale ranging from 1 (extreme left) to 10 (extreme right). 24 We measure this with the question: “As far as you can remember, which of the two sides that fought the Civil War did your family most identify with, the Republicans or the Nationalists?” [“Nationalists” is the name that was given to Franco’s supporters during the Civil War]. Possible responses are: 1 = Nationalist; 2 = Republicans; 3 = Both; 4 = Neither. This question has been used in previous surveys conducted by the CIS. In our survey, the response rate to this question (77%) was higher than in any previous one. We include this variable in the regressions as two different dummies: Family Nationalist Side, and Family Republican Side. 25 “When you were a child or adolescent, how much did they talk about politics at home?”: 4 = Very much; 3 = Quite a lot; 2 = A little; 1 = Not at all. 26 To be consistent with the traditional male preeminence in Spanish culture we use father’s position on the ideological scale. The correlation between the father’s ideology and the mother’s is very high (0.77), so we cannot include both of them in the same regressions. Using the mother’s ideology implies no change in our results (these are available upon request). Since our indicator was reported by the respondent, some bias may exist (i.e. the respondent bringing her father closer to her ideological   43                                                                                                                                                                                positions). Yet, the correlation between the respondent’s ideology and her father’s is not dramatically high (0.55). 27 We do not take into account victimization by the Republican side during the Civil War, as we would not expect this to have straightforward effects on attitudes towards TJ. As we explained, victims of the Republican side received reparations in the past. Current TJ measures are connected to reparation for Francoist violations. 28 Victimization includes any of the following: death in combat; death in bombardment; homicide; death penalty; disappearance; imprisonment; flight from Spain; was forced into hiding; was expelled from work. We label this variable “Victim of Nationalist Side during CW”. 29 This includes any of the following: arrest; imprisonment; was expelled from work; was fined; was forced to leave the country; was executed. We label this variable “Victim of Francoism”. 30 Due to the limited number of cases in the group of people with direct victimizing experiences, we include family and individual victimization experiences together. We have also run analyses without those with personal victimizing experiences, and the results are consistent. 31 According to Thoms et al. (2008: 81),”different regions (…) are likely to have quite different views on TJ”, and they recommend “over-sampling”, as we have done in our study. 32 The rate of “doesn’t know” responses is 16.12% for truth commissions, 14.7% for trials, and 9.91% for symbols. We must bear in mind that the question about the creation of a truth commission had a different set of response categories than the others; in this case, the intermediate category of “indifferent” is absent, which may have pushed the respondents toward either one of the two extremes: agree-disagree.   44                                                                                                                                                                                33 Note that missing data implies a reduction in the size of the sample used for the estimations of models presented in tables 1, 2, and 3. Re-estimating them using selection models that correct for potential selection bias in our dependent variables implies no changes to our conclusions. 34 Though we do not have enough space to develop on the differences between Basques and Catalans regarding their support of TJ policies, one explanation could be that Basque nationalism is more extreme than Catalan. While in the Basque Country there is a significant tendency to consider Spanish and Basque identities as incompatible, in Catalonia dual identities (people feeling simultaneously Spanish and Catalan) are more frequent (this can be seen in our survey: available upon request). Given that Francoism was characterized by the aggressive imposition of Spanish identity and the repression of minority identities, a more extreme ethnic identity may be leaning towards a greater support for TJ measures. 35 Similarly, in the South African case it has been confirmed that “young blacks are not more likely to be reconciled than older blacks” (Gibson, 2004b: 215). 36 This result ties in with Gibson’s (2004a) finding regarding the importance of racial identities in explaining the acceptance of TJ measures in South Africa. 37 In most of the few existing studies based on survey data, support for TJ measures shows to be more common than the opposite (Thoms et al, 2008: 78).  work_iwtxgge6ubc6vezfcxx7virz5m ---- SE_01.indd do i: 10 .7 21 3/ ur be .0 6. 00 2. SE 01 I SS N 21 75 -3 36 9 Lic en cia do so b um a Lic en ça C re at iv e Co m m on s urbe. Revista Brasileira de Gestão Urbana (Brazilian Journal of Urban Management), v. 6, n. 2, p. 158-169, maio/ago. 2014 Social Justice and the “Green” City1 Justiça social e a cidade “verde” Liette Gilbert Ph.D in Urban Planning (UCLA), professor at Faculty of Environmental Studies, York University, Toronto, ON - Canada, e-mail: gilbertl@yorku.ca Abstract A transition to a new, greener urbanism is increasingly imperative in the face of environmental crises. However, such a transition is not possible without considering social justice. This essay examines some ten- sions between social justice and urban sustainability and some of the reasons why a social justice approach to urban sustainability is often marginalized by a neoliberal sustainability ontology. This essay irst engages with various normative concepts of social justice and its long existing but unful illed claim in the city. It then considers some gains toward greener urbanism but contends that urban sustainability responses have ge- nerally been more preoccupied with ecological modernization and the reproduction of best practices rather than with socio-spatial justice. In looking at some workings of green neoliberalism, the essay points to how the ecological is easily recuperated for neoliberal ends. The last section addresses some reasons why the social is de-privileged in the dominant sustainability discourses and practices, and how social justice serves, through citizenship practices, as a claim to urban change where participation is not a bureaucratized process but an everyday practice. Overall, the essay cautions against certain sustainability discourses and green neoliberalism without addressing its ingrained inequalities. Keywords: Social justice. Just city. Good city. Greening. Green neoliberalism. Resumo A transição em direção a um urbanismo “mais verde” se faz cada vez mais necessária devido a crise ambiental. Contudo, essa transição somente é possível se acompanhada de justiça social. Assim, tem-se por objetivo investigar algumas tensões entre a justiça social e a sustentabilidade urbana, bem como algumas das razões pelas quais uma abordagem de justiça social voltada à sustentabilidade urbana é frequentemente marginaliza- da por uma ontologia sustentável neoliberal. Este artigo se inicia com a apresentação de diversos conceitos 1 My thanks go to Dr. Alexandre Babak Hedjazi for inviting me to participate in the ICE-NET Urban Futures and Transitions conference. I am grateful for the excellent comments of many participants and the four URBE reviewers. urbe. Revista Brasileira de Gestão Urbana (Brazilian Journal of Urban Management), v. 6, n. 2, p. 158-169, maio/ago. 2014 Social Justice and the “Green” City 159 Introduction In his very in luential book, Social Justice and the City, published forty years ago and still of great relevance in the face of widening urban inequalities produced by neoliberal capitalism, David Harvey (1973, p. 314) contends that a revolutionary practice can only accomplish the transition from “[…] an urbanism based in exploitation to an urbanism appropriate for the human [and other] species.” In many urban contexts, such transition is increasingly presented as an imperative in the face of ecological destruction and obsolete urban infrastructure. Without rejecting the need for an “ecological” revolution, a “green” urban transition seems impossible without a redistributive purpose, social justice, and social change. This essay contends that social justice, as a claim and means for addressing equity de icits, has often been neglected in dominant sustainability discourses that drive the development of “greener” cities. Such an argument is not necessarily new but remains critical because sustainability, often articulated in the economic language of the triple bottom line, mobilizes the environment at the service of pro it-driven agendas, which further exacerbate social divides (AGYEMAN; BULLARD; EVANS, 2012; DAVIDSON et al., 2012). To speak of social justice is not simply to demand a redistribution of environmental and economic opportunities but to recognize that some practices deemed ‘sustainable’ hide and aggravate already existing equity de icits. Social justice, in theory and in practice, seeks to alleviate and close these equity de icits without rejecting the promises of a more ecologically friendly or economically vibrant city. To be skeptical of dominant sustainability discourses does not mean denying the possibilities of urban transitions and social change. A focus on social justice reveals the misleading balance depicted in the rhetoric of the three pillars of sustainability: economy, environment and society. The metaphor of the three pillars, often graphically depicted as three identical and slightly overlapping circles, three similar mutually chasing green arrows or three perfectly matching architectural columns, obscures the unequal relationships between the economic, environmental and social dimensions of sustainability (or other synonymous triads, such as pro it, planet, people). Although sustainability and sustainable development has multiple meanings and inevitably, multiple performances, the economic pillar is often recognized as having a greater bearing over the social and environmental components normativos de justiça social e sua longa reivindicação (existente, mas não suprida) na cidade. Posteriormente são discutidos alguns bene ícios decorrentes de um urbanismo “mais verde”, alegando-se, contudo, que as ações de sustentabilidade urbana têm, de forma geral, concentrado-se mais em aspectos relacionados à modernização ecológica e reprodução de boas práticas do que em questões voltadas à justiça socioespacial. Ao se analisarem trabalhos sobre “neoliberalismo verde”, o artigo evidencia como o tema da ecologia é restabelecido para objetivos neoliberais. A última seção debate o motivo pelo qual o aspecto social é relegado a segundo plano no discurso e práxis dominante de sustentabilidade e a forma pela qual a justiça social serve, por meio das práticas de cidadania, como reivindicação para transformações urbanas em locais onde a participação popular encontra-se arraigada na prática diária. Em linhas gerais, o artigo alerta contra determinados discursos de sustentabilidade e “neoliberalismo verde” sem abordar suas desigualdades arraigadas. Palavras-chave: Justiça social. Cidade justa. Boa cidade. Greening. Neoliberalismo verde. Sustainability is both an honorable goal for carefully de ined purposes and a camou laged trap for the well-intentioned unwary (MARCUSE, 1998, p. 104). urbe. Revista Brasileira de Gestão Urbana (Brazilian Journal of Urban Management), v. 6, n. 2, p. 158-169, maio/ago. 2014 GILBERT, L.160 (MARCUSE, 1998; FOLADORI, 1999; AGYEMAN; BULLARD; EVANS, 2012; DAVIDSON et al., 2012; LUKE, 2013). Despite their interdependence, social and environmental concerns appear more easily trivialized and marginalized at the pro it of economic growth. Increasing poverty and the growing gulf between the “haves” and the “have nots”, irreversible environmental changes, continuous resource depletion and the constant degradation of natural environments all demonstrate that sustainability as an integrated approach remains an ideological goal and a constant challenge. By focusing on social justice, my objective is not only to point to de iciencies in the ‘green’ city model but also to insist on the possibility and necessity to bridge such gaps and hold the idea of sustainability to its professed goals. However, to hold sustainability to its ideals, social justice in the city must address past and continuing uneven development processes in urban spaces. This is not a simple task given the accumulated social and environmental injustices in the city, and particularly in lower-income neighborhoods, which are rarely the objective of innovative green agendas. Social justice and urban sustainability are contested terms and may not always share compatible objectives, but their multiple and elastic meanings may nevertheless provide some room for overlap and signi icant change (DOBSON, 2012). This essay examines some tensions between social justice and urban sustainability and some of the reasons why a social justice approach to urban sustainability is often marginalized by a neoliberal sustainability ontology. This essay irst engages with various normative concepts of social justice and its long existing but unful illed claim in the city. The paper then considers some gains in greener urbanism but contends that urban sustainability responses have generally been more preoccupied with ecological modernization and the reproduction of best practices rather than with socio-spatial justice. In looking at some workings of green neoliberalism, the essay points to how the ecological is easily recuperated for neoliberal ends. The last section addresses some reasons why the social is de-privileged in the dominant sustainability discourses and practices, and how social justice serves, through citizenship practices, as a claim to urban change where participation is not a bureaucratized process but an everyday practice. Social justice in the city Harvey (1973, p. 97) de ines social justice as “[…] a particular application of just principles to con licts arising out of the necessity for social cooperation in seeking individual advancement.” Such a de inition, with all of its normative and ideological underpinnings, makes obvious that cities are spaces of marginalization and discrimination that necessitate some redress in both “the division of bene its and the allocation of burdens” associated with urban production and distribution if we are to live up to the expectations of a just city (HARVEY, 1973, p. 97) For Harvey (1973, p. 101), social justice is irst contingent on the “just distribution” of opportunities along class lines, and he considers “need, contribution to common good, and merit” as three basic criteria for a “territorial distributive justice.” Although need is a highly relative concept, it is here understood as basic activities (e.g., food, housing, health care, education, etc.), and Harvey (1973, p. 107) astutely points to the “difference between needs and actual allocations” as a practical means to evaluate injustices. Additionally, this difference enables us to see how the production of a “common good” (or “common bad” for that matter) bene its or marginalizes particular groups and individuals in the city. For Harvey (1973, p. 107), merit is not associated with individual worth but rather with security, access and the re- distribution of resources necessary to “compensate for the degree of social and natural environmental dif iculty” extended to particular groups, individuals, and neighborhoods. Harvey (1973) describes social justice as a set of principles necessary for resolving con licting claims arising from the social and institutional arrangements associated with production and distribution activities. Harvey’s particular contribution rests on the emphasis of both the distribution of opportunities and the rarely acknowledged social production of surpluses or scarcity in the city. Observing how surplus is distributed in “socially undesirable ways” for populations that additionally often bear the brunt of scarcity, Harvey (1973, p. 115) summarizes the urbe. Revista Brasileira de Gestão Urbana (Brazilian Journal of Urban Management), v. 6, n. 2, p. 158-169, maio/ago. 2014 Social Justice and the “Green” City 161 challenge of aspiring to social justice in the city when he writes: [i]n contemporary “advanced” societies the problem is to devise alternatives to the market mechanism which allow the transference of productive power and the distribution of surplus to sectors and territories where the social necessities are so patently obvious. Drawing on Harvey (1973), many urban scholars have attempted normative de initions of ‘just’ or ‘good’ city. Susan Fainstein (2010, 2005) contends that in the ‘just city’, justice should be the moral basis for urban planning. Urban justice, for Fainstein (2010, 2005), is based on the principles of diversity, democracy, and equity, and such principles ought to be considered and mindfully furthered in planning practices and policies. While emphasizing these principles, Fainstein recognizes the con licting and even contradictory tensions between them but nevertheless insists that material equality, equal opportunity and recognition of difference are crucial in determining what is distributed and who bene its from such distribution. In Fainstein’s ‘just city’, justice intervention seeks equitable or redistributive outcomes for people through a critique of the dominant neoliberal approach to planning. Fainstein’s urban theory of justice is therefore a call to redirect practitioners from neoliberal economic development to social equity. In her view, justice should be “the irst evaluative criterion used in policy making” (FAINSTEIN, 2010, p. 6). Fainstein (2010) speci ically calls for considering social equity in the production of the city (by illustrating equity de icits in empirical cases), but her focus is geared particularly toward the politics of urban growth and planning rather than toward Harvey (1973) larger conceptual formulations and capitalist economic processes (i.e., the systematic causes of equity de icits). The ‘good city’ is a sibling concept of the ‘just city.’ With more than ifty years of thinking about cities in the Global South and North, John Friedmann (2000, 2002) identi ies human lourishing and multiplicity as the foundations of what he sees as the ‘good city.’ The materiality of the ‘good city’ is found concretely in affordable housing and health care, adequate work and social provisions, and the good governance of these outcomes. Friedmann (2002), similar to Fainstein (2010), calls for planners to engage in the material and structural transformation of cities to address ongoing inequalities. As in the ‘just city’, equity is the central foundation of the ‘good city’. Thus, for Friedmann (2000, p. 466), “[e]very human being has the right, by nature, to the full development of their innate intellectual, physical and spiritual potentials in the context of wider communities.” Such a right, Friedmann (2000) contends, is the most basic human right. However, such a right implies an intrinsic mutuality because, for Friedmann (2000, p. 465), “[…] no group can be completely free until freedom [from oppression] has been achieved for every group.” Here rests the challenge and the promise of Friedmann’s (1987) radical transformative practice for freedom and justice to be rendered and enacted more equitably. Building on Friedmann, Ash Amin (2006, p. 1013) suggests that the ‘good city’ and the politics of ‘living together’ can be thought of as a challenge to fashion a “[…] progressive politics of well-being and emancipation out of multiplicity and difference and from the particularities of the urban experience.” In doing so, Amin (2006, p. 1013) suggests “four registers of urban solidarity” (repair, relatedness, rights and re-enchantment) that engage with multiplicity through everyday urban life. For Amin (2006, p. 1016), solidarity means ensuring universal and affordable access to basics services (shelter, sanitation, sustenance, etc.) as well as amending the “[…] damage wrought by the fear, hate and anxiety that feeds on division and envy in urban life […]”. To do so, Amin (2006) argues for the right of all citizens to participate in urban life and to bene it from it in the form of “participative parity” (FRASER, 2005, p. 87) rather than routinized participation serving processes, ideas, and the people in power. What these normative attempts to de ine the ‘just city’ or the ‘good city’ have in common are the practice of justice, access, right, and redress of inequalities. While normative de initions are certainly problematic when they pretend a universality, the discussion around the ‘just city’ and the ‘good city’ seeks to address rather than occult urban injustices. By articulating principles of social justice, equality and mutuality, the concepts of ‘just city’ and ‘good city’ clearly state urbe. Revista Brasileira de Gestão Urbana (Brazilian Journal of Urban Management), v. 6, n. 2, p. 158-169, maio/ago. 2014 GILBERT, L.162 the needs to review processes of urban planning production and distribution in order to alleviate its discriminatory effects and live up the ideals of equity and social justice. In 2000, Polèse and Stren used the speci ic language of social sustainability to examine how urban political and physical infrastructures were to address the growing diversity and the management of change. Polèse and Stren (2000, p. 15-16) de ine social sustainability as development (or growth) that is compatible with the harmonious evolution of civil society, fostering and environment conducive to the compatible cohabitation of culturally and socially diverse groups while at the same time encouraging social integration, with improvements in the quality of life for all segments of the population. Similarly to others social justice scholars, the authors insisted that the achievement of social sustainability requires local institutions and governments to […] reduce both the level of exclusion of marginal and/or disadvantaged groups, and the degree of social and spatial fragmentation that both encourages and re lects this exclusionary pattern […] (POLÈSE; STREN, 2000, p. 16). Although a broad concept, social sustainability ought to be more than an element of the sus- tainability trialectics, adding social actors into the mix of more popularized discourses of environmen- tal and economic sustainability. In considering social sustainability as a challenge to exclusion and marginalization rather than a complementary instrument or component of a prosperous economy balanced with ecological integrity, social justice demands a rearticulation of the material processes of the city. Peter Marcuse (1998) insightfully notes that the current discourse of sustainability does not necessarily insure social justice - i.e., building a new social order based on equality and justice for all in every aspect of social life - and has rather been more frequently used to sustain an unjust status quo. Yet the prevalent tropes of social sustainability, such as empowerment, social cohesion, social capital, well-being and quality of life, resilience and livability have perhaps at times shifted our attention away from addressing persistent inequalities and democratic de icits. If social sustainability is to become more than rhetoric, social justice is required to redress the continuing marginalization that has long existed in racialized, low-income and immigrant communities and neighborhoods. When speaking of diversity and difference in the city, it is tempting to conclude that what has been sustained over time, despite the best planning intentions of the past decades, is exclusion and marginalization. Social sustainability cannot be simplistically understood as the establishment of social arrangements that enable democratic politics (DAVIDSON, 2009). Such arrangements require institutional transformations that irst question how such arrangements are produced and reproduce social exclusion and marginalization as well as environmental deterioration. Urban sustainability Since 1987 and the Brundtland Commission Report’s (WCED, 1987, p. 41) oft-quoted de inition of sustainable development as “[…] development that meets the needs of the present without compromising the ability of future generations to meet their own needs,” sustainability has become a dominant discourse, treating development and environment as one single (arguably oxymoronic) issue. The sustainability of cities and the need to develop and foster an integrated holistic vision for urban sustainability has been generally promoted through a double discourse of urgency. On the one hand, the world has increasingly become urbanized with more than half of the world’s population already living in cities. On the other hand, cities have often been seen as ecologically destructive, ‘unnatural’, and the antithesis of nature. Despite the growing scholarship examining cities and nature as interacting and inextricably connected processes - best captured by David Harvey (1996) claim that there is nothing ‘unnatural’ about New York City - the discourse of urban sustainability has been particularly focused on mitigating the detrimental and harmful effects of urban development (KEIL, 2003; BRAUN, 2005; GANDY, 2002). Beatley (1999) refers to green urbanism urbe. Revista Brasileira de Gestão Urbana (Brazilian Journal of Urban Management), v. 6, n. 2, p. 158-169, maio/ago. 2014 Social Justice and the “Green” City 163 as the practice of creating communities mutually bene icial to humans and the environment (i.e., ecological processes). Urban sustainability and green urbanism are also a call for urban planners and designers to do things differently. Prior to sustainability being naturalized into urban planning and policy in the 1990s, early ecological activists and innovators (e.g., Buckminster Fuller, John Todd, Ian McHarg, etc.) argued the urgent need to promote sustainability and strongly believed that the environmental crisis was in fact a design crisis (VAN DER RYN; COWAN, 1996). For example, experimental architecture based on renewable sources of energy was a way to prove our technological ability to support human needs in the face of the inite resources of the planet. Problems of unsustainability were generally perceived as a matter of better integrating cities with their physical environments (HOUGH, 1995; VAN DER RYN; COWAN, 1996; BEATLEY, 1999). Thus, ecological designers embraced sustainability for its ecological tenets and emphasized the obligation to rede ine the relations between ecological systems and between people and the environment. Some conventional urban planning practices were slowly replaced by a greener, ecological, more sustainable rationality where environmental problems were often relegated to technological considerations. Such ecological modernization or sustainability ix approaches were perceived as the most ef icient and effective use and management of resources but showed limited preoccupation with social and economic issues. Often emphasizing the protection or restoration of ecological processes, ecological design through a sustainable or greening city agenda focused on solving problems “by changing the city, not by changing society” (BRAUN, 2005, p. 638). In this sense, the greening of cities has often been considered “largely atheoretical and apolitical” (BRAUN, 2005, p. 638). The ongoing dif iculty of reconciling the social, economic and ecological imperatives of urban sustainability does not mean that there have not been some successful efforts or achievements in terms of greater energy ef iciency, ecological processes restoration, and waste recycling. Urban planning and design have long relied on historical precedence as a way of studying, comparing and conceiving plans. In recent years, many so-called ‘best practices’ of urban sustainability have been traveling as aspiring norms and inspiring benchmarks toward greater urban sustainability. In fact, best practices are often seen as effective means for promoting urban sustainability (BULKELEY, 2006). Numerous non-governmental organizations and transnational networks dedicated to the promotion of urban sustainability (e.g., UN- Habitat Sustainable Cities Program or ICLEI) and numerous scholarly books (BEATLEY, 1999; ZETTER; WATSON, 2006; COLANTONIO; DIXON, 2011; HALL, 2013) spotlight examples of green urban revitalization ranging from climate initiatives to greener transport, from energy ef icient buildings to waste production and management programs, and from greener infrastructure and services to green management governance practices (e.g., sustainable procurement, eco-budgeting, etc.). Many cities have used their green plans and developments as competitive advantages, positioning themselves as best practices to emulate. Among the most celebrated examples of urban sustainability, cities such as Stockholm, Hamburg, Copenhagen, San Francisco, Vancouver as well as Curitiba, Medellín and Songa are recognized as leaders in committing to green initiatives and achieving environmental standards. Ranking the greenest cities has become a growing popular global endeavor led by a multitude of actors, such as The Economist in collaboration with the technological company Siemens (2012), Reuters Environmental forum (2010), Organic Gardening (2014) and Globe Award (2014), among many others. Urban sustainability has brought the beginning of a much needed ecological consciousness to urban planning (related to energy consumption, integrity of habitats, green spaces, reuse and recycling materials, housing density, and levels of pollution of air and water, among other issues) but best practices also represent a political rationality through which cities, organizations, and networks promote and legitimate their particular vision of urban sustainability. Their hope is that their initiatives, programs, and agendas will inspire policy change elsewhere, notwithstanding local conditions or capacities. Little concern is given to the “underlying premises and beliefs, with processes of learning con ined to those of lesson drawing” and the “consequent implications for the governing of urban sustainability” (BULKELEY, 2006, p. 1033, urbe. Revista Brasileira de Gestão Urbana (Brazilian Journal of Urban Management), v. 6, n. 2, p. 158-169, maio/ago. 2014 GILBERT, L.164 1035). There are certainly some bene its to shared learning about urban sustainability’s best practices to encourage a “sustainable” vision of cities. However, there are obvious dif iculties linked to numerical measurement and ranking something as subjective, dynamic and evolving as cities. The capacity of current assessment tools, indicators and indexes to measure the complexities of sustainability has also been increasingly contested. Davidson et al. (2012) point to the fact that the conventional liberal model of sustainability (and its three pillars) tends to prioritize the economy as the most important sphere of sustainability and to oversimplify the idea of harmony between economic, environmental and social dimensions. As Davidson et al. (2012, p. 58) remind us, there are also problems related to […] the lack of de initional clarity in some assessment tools about what is being measured, weak epistemological links between the de inition of sustainability and indicators, limited emphasis of social sustainability and the entrenchment of an economic paradigm in these assessment tools. Moreover, as Bulkeley (2006, p. 1029) rightly states: In the promotion of urban sustainability in national and international arenas, numerous initiatives and programs have been put in place to facilitate the creation and the dissemination of ‘best practice’ through which to promote policy transfer and learning. However, despite the vast array of available best practices, little is known about the ways in which best practice is constructed, used, and contested, or of its implications for urban sustainability. T h e d i s c o u r s e o f s u s t a i n a b i l i t y h a s b e e n naturalized in cities, often at the detriment of local knowledge, particularly governance cultures, place-speci ic intricacies, and historical speci icities. In the context of cities, ‘sustainable’ is often used interchangeably with a series of catchy, inde inite and equivocal terms, such as green, resilient, livable, healthy, happy, biodiverse, biophillic, and so forth. The predominant commitments of urban sustainability and green urbanism for renewable energy, zero waste, spatial mobility, ecosystem integrity, and food security (all good t h i n g s ) ra re ly n a m e t h e p re - ex i s t i n g s o c i a l inequalities and injustices that characterize cities. When they do address social issues, such as the ICLEI’s (INTERNATIONAL COUNCIL FOR LOCAL ENVIRONMENTAL INITIATIVES, 2013) de inition of green urban economy as “productive and socially inclusive”, this inclusivity is increasingly expressed in the prospect of green jobs. Work is certainly a crucial component of social inclusivity but it may not be suf icient to fully address social inequalities because, as Davidson et al. (2012, p. 59) note, [t]he classic con lict between jobs and the environmental more often than not results in economic development taking precedence with a degree of environmental compromise being applied. If, as David Harvey (1973, p. 156) reminds us, urbanism is “[…] a set of social relationships which re lects the relationships established throughout society as a whole […],” then green urbanism should not only feature a greener approach but should also run counter to vested interests that produce and regulate unjust and inequitable urbanism. Urbanism as a social form is not limited to the built environment but also includes its actual mode of production. Too often, greening is limited to the form or outcome rather than a challenge to the market forces tapping into environmental sustainability rhetoric. Thus, key questions remain: what is sustained, and who bene its and loses from sustainability discourse and programs? Green neoliberalism Who does not want to live in a sustainable world? Who does not want a greener economy that promotes or invigorates economic growth while also preventing climate change, the dwindling of natural resources, food insecurity, the loss of biodiversity and ecosystems? In the last decade, green neoliberalism (i.e., the convergence of market forces and environmentally friendly logic) has permeated many aspects of our lives from wide-ranging eco-friendly products to corporate eco-manifestos to governmental agendas bolstering urbe. Revista Brasileira de Gestão Urbana (Brazilian Journal of Urban Management), v. 6, n. 2, p. 158-169, maio/ago. 2014 Social Justice and the “Green” City 165 green jobs. Although there have been sincere green efforts (e.g., towards ecological protection), much of the sustainability rhetoric embodied in green neoliberalism and its variations of eco-capitalism, green consumerism, bio-economy and corporate eco-credentials often amount to more trumpeting than action. Greenwashing has been a perverse way to stimulate the market for more consumer goods and services. Despite their best intentions, greening discourse (and its underlying moral discourse of responsibility, scarcity and altruism) endorsed by some businesses, governments, non- pro it organizations and consumers alike adhere to constant externalization, vague tropes, misleading claims or outright falsi ication to convince the general public that they are ‘doing the right thing’ to save the planet. Green neoliberalism is still neoliberalism that favors invasion of market processes in social and political life. It is not enough to promote the recycling of plastic bottles without questioning the privatization of water. Luke (2013, 89) vividly illustrates the neoliberal ethic of ‘reduce-reuse-recycle’ when he states: [b]y using recycled steel, plastic bottles, tires, blue jeans and cotton to build a new 2013 Ford car body, dashboard, engine gaskets, carpet and sound dampening, what was old and worthless becomes newly pro itable again, and neither the automotive industry and car reliance nor the global oil crisis are questioned. As Khosla (2005, p. 23) remarks [i]n this age of magical marketing, ideological tricks are being manipulated with new zeal, and it behooves us to look deeper than the surface symptoms, signs and symbols of oppression. Green neoliberalism does not challenge the current economic and political systems, and for some businesses, governments and organizations, its nonthreatening appeal is highly pro itable. As Luke (2013, p. 83) reminds us: […] the ethics behind the uneasy merger of sustainability and development are aimed at preserving not the Earth, but rather the power, privilege and position attained by businesses developing their markets. Eco-ef iciency, for example, is environmentally good and commendable but also highly pro- itable when it ignores the social costs for individuals or groups who bear the brunt of that cost. The so-called “triple bottom line” (allegedly reconciling pro its, planet and people) often sums up into a “reshaping of environmental crisis to the market’s ends” (ROGERS, 2009). Green(er) capitalism rarely divulges full information to consumers or, as Žižek’s (2011) comments, surreptitiously packages it into a “Starbucks logic” where customers are not only buying a commodity but also buying a logic of ethical and environmental consciousness (i.e., ethical sourcing and responsibly grown coffee, global environmental stewardship, and local community involvement) embodied in the product and corporate image. As Harvey (1973, p. 156) argues, commodity refers to a speci ic product but also to a set of social relationships. Rogers (2009) succinctly summarizes the functioning of this “greener” logic of neoliberalism when she writes [ i ] n s t e a d o f o u r g r e a t e r e n v i r o n m e n t a l consciousness transforming the way business is conducted, what we more often see is the market contorting ecological problems so they it into some sort of pro itable framework. Yet, Rogers (2009) insists that consumers should not be paralyzed by such logic but rather politicized because “[t]o bring about change we must experience ourselves as political actors and not simply shoppers who are supposed to vote with our wallets.” Greening, or the process of transforming spaces and lifestyles into allegedly more environmentally friendly practices, however, should be at the service of redistributive justice rather than solely competitiveness and growth. A green or sustainable economy does not automatically ful ill redistributive justice if what is sustained is the same urbanism driven by pro its and inequalities – even when presented in a slightly greener shade. Sustaining Social Justice There are various reasons why the social is often relegated to lower or after-thought considerations. urbe. Revista Brasileira de Gestão Urbana (Brazilian Journal of Urban Management), v. 6, n. 2, p. 158-169, maio/ago. 2014 GILBERT, L.166 The quantitative prominence of the economic dimension and the dif iculty to balance the social and environmental implications of sustainability tend to avoid the far more dif icult need for relational or interdependency analysis. Sustainability is holistic and interdisciplinary in intention but not necessary in measurement practices (DAVIDSON et al., 2012; FOLADORI, 1999). Measuring sustainability is more often than not approached from a disci- plinary perspective (FOLADORI, 1999). Economic measurements are based on the methodology of liberal economics where intergenerational and intragenerational (equity) social relations and social differences are dif icult to account for and are at best average, thus obscuring rather than detecting differences (FOLADORI, 1999). Although it is possible to quantify social inequality, such measurements often remain detached from historical economic organization (production, distribution and consumption of services and activities) and their social relationships (HARVEY, 1973; MARCUSE, 1998; FOLADORI, 1999). Moreover, although sustain- ability is inevitably an interdisciplinary concept, measurements and policy mandates tend to be fragmented along jurisdictional and geographical lines (FOLADORI, 1999; DAVIDSON et al., 2012). Thus, the tensions between the three pillars of sustainability are not only due to the facts that capitalism is built on social inequalities and environmental injustices but also in the fact that the environmental and social are weighted differently and manipulated more easily in such system. State and planning institutions have long professed to be concerned with equity without necessarily delivering equitable outcomes. As Dale, Dushenko and Robinson (2012, p.13-14) remind us [a]fter twenty-odd years of struggling with sustainable development at the local scale, we as practitioners, scholars and educators ind ourselves with an implementation de icit… The implementation gap appears to be underpinned by a fundamental gridlock of overlapping and often con licting government jurisdictions, path dependencies, technological lock-in and institutional rigidities. This implementation gap limits and erodes the possibility of everyday citizenship. Everyday citizenship has been an object of struggle for different groups to claim various rights for themselves; it has been a fundamental vehicle through which people have sought social justice, recognition of their marginalization and needs, and participation in the political realm. This performance of substantive and differentiated citizenship sought to enable groups and individuals to make particular claims to reaf irm and rearticulate their rights. The struggle for recognition and social justice generally revolves around claims for inclusion in the polity in which one justly seeks membership in a qualitatively different way. Whatever their particular identities, interests or spatial scales, political citizenship actions aim at breaking down the processes producing inequalities. The city becomes the political space where the articulation and claiming of new citizenship rights becomes possible because it is the sphere of everyday interactions where changing mentalities become possible through battles over urban issues and urban policies (often as a proxy for larger struggles). As Edward Soja (1989, p. 6) reminds us, [w]e must be insistently aware of how space can be made to hide consequences for us, how relations of power and discipline are inscribed into the apparently innocent spatiality of social life. Thus, the urban is both the sphere of where citizenship becomes rhizomatic, i.e., connecting to any or multiple communities, and where mobilizations of residents, networks, and institutions potentially arise against unequal relationships of power. Central to social justice is the right to participate, the right to difference. Lefebvre’s (1968) right to difference was motivated by the rapid changes of industrialization and urbanization of the 1960s. Lefebvre (1968) develops the concept of “difference” as a challenge to the ideology of alienation, homogeneity, and marginalization. The right to difference is a fundamental principle in the struggle for democracy – and holding the tenets of democratic freedom and equality to its professed ideals. For Lefebvre (1968), the right to difference is expressed through the right to the city, i.e., the right to resist dominating and oppressive conditions by engaging and participating in an alternative that urbe. Revista Brasileira de Gestão Urbana (Brazilian Journal of Urban Management), v. 6, n. 2, p. 158-169, maio/ago. 2014 Social Justice and the “Green” City 167 reasserts social realities into political ideologies and market strategies. The right to difference is the right to claim, to struggle, and to rede ine the relationship between alienation and appropriation. It is the right to urban change. The reinsertion of the social into the political and economic enables the practices and performances of everyday rights (right to work, education, health, housing, services, etc.) – the right to claim rights. As David Harvey (2008, p. 23) claims: The right to the city is far more than the indi- vidual liberty to access urban resources: it is a right to change ourselves by changing the city. It is, moreover, a common rather than an individual right because this transformation inevitably depends upon the exercise of a collective power to reshape the processes of urbanization. The freedom to make and remake our cities and ourselves is, I want to argue, one of the most precious yet most neglected of our human rights. T h e r i g h t to a p p ro p r i a te u r b a n s p a c e i s carried through the right to participation, i.e., the involvement of residents/citizens/inhabitants to institutionalized control over urban life, including participation in political life, and the management and administration of the city (DIKEÇ, 2001). However, participation must be meaningful to yield change and cannot be routinized as an administrative or bureaucratized process, as we often see, for example, in planning or urban (re) development processes. Lefebvre’s (1968) right to the city is a claim for active participation in society without parameters established by the status quo. The right to the city and to difference is aimed at ighting discrimination and repression through a reinvention or rede inition of the political and the development of a new urban/societal ethics. The right to the city calls for the right not to be excluded. It calls for a new centrality, a renewed urban society, a different urban mode of production – one that embodies social justice and an ecological consciousness. For Lefebvre (1968) and Harvey (2003), the right to the city is not only a right to access the existing but explicitly a right to transform, a right to remake ourselves by creating a different type of urbanism, a new urban future. Conclusion The discourses of sustainability and greening do not necessarily take us to the future but rather to the status quo if redressing inequality is not at the core of such agendas. Claims for social justice are not about political correctness or environmental awareness but about claims of inclusion for people who have been marginalized by urban processes. Justice and equity claims are challenging to realize but social justice remains an important concept that should be closely examined. Additionally, the differences between discourses and the materialities of sustainability, between social needs and urban allocations, between planning ideology and im plementation, between what Marcuse (1998, p. 104) sees as the contested performance of sustainability as an “honourable goal” and as a “camou laged trap” should be denounced. Urban transitions motivated by green neoliberalism will only aggravate existing polarization given that such urban transition generally occurs on the backs of marginalized communities, further silencing them. A just urban transition will not only improve ineffective transportation systems and create new green jobs, it will also give a voice and the ability to act to the people. Envisioning and transitioning toward a greener urbanism is not simply an exercise in planning for the future; it must also account for past and present injustices. In calling our attention to the hidden assumptions of urbanism, Lipsitz (1998, p. 2) calls for “a presence of mind” (drawing from Walter Benjamin) – an awareness of the present moment to shape a different future. Urban transition should not be an excuse to disguise or ignore the exploitative practices of conventional or green urbanism because, as David Harvey (1973, p. 43) states: “we cannot resolve dif iculties by pretending they do not exist”. Such an approach has been predominant for too long and any urban transition toward a greener urbanism without social justice blunts its revolutionary potential. urbe. Revista Brasileira de Gestão Urbana (Brazilian Journal of Urban Management), v. 6, n. 2, p. 158-169, maio/ago. 2014 GILBERT, L.168 References AGYEMAN, J.; BULLARD, R. D.; EVANS, B. (Ed.). Just sustainabilities: development in an unequal world. London: Taylor & Francis, 2012. AMIN, A. The good city. Urban Studies, v. 43, n. 5-6, p . 1 0 0 9 - 1 0 2 3 , 2 0 0 6 . h t t p : / / d x . d o i . o r g / 1 0 . 1 0 8 0 /00420980600676717 BEATLEY, T. Green urbanism: learning from european cities. Washington: Island Press, 1999. BRAUN, B. Environmental issues: writing a more- than-human urban geography. Progress in Human Geography, v. 29, n. 5, p. 635-650, 2005. http://dx.doi. org/10.1191/0309132505ph574pr BULKELEY, H. Urban sustainability: learning from best practice? Environment and Planning A, v. 38, n. 6, p. 1029-1044, 2006. http://dx.doi.org/10.1068/a37300 COLANTONIO, A.; DIXON, T. Urban regeneration and social sustainability: best practice from european cities. New York: Wiley, 2011. DALE, A.; DUSHENKO, W.; ROBINSON, P. J. (Ed.). Urban sustainability: reconnecting space and place. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2012. 296 p. DAVIDSON, K. M. et al. Assessing urban sustainability from a social democratic perspective: a thematic approach. Local Environment, v. 17, n. 1, p. 57-73, 2012. http:// dx.doi.org/10.1080/13549839.2011.631990 DAVIDSON, M. Social sustainability: a potential for politics? Local Environment, v. 14, n. 7, p. 607-619, 2009. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/13549830903089291 D I K E Ç , M . J u s t i c e a n d t h e s p a t i a l i m a g i n a t i o n . Environment and Planning A, v. 33, n. 10, p. 1785- 1805, 2001. http://dx.doi.org/10.1068/a3467 DOBSON, A. Social justice and environmental sustainabi- lity: ne’er the twain shall meet. In: AGYEMAN, J.; BULLARD, R. D.; EVANS, B. (Ed.). Just sustainabilities: development in an unequal world. London: Taylor & Francis, 2012. FAINSTEIN, S. S. The just city. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2010. 224 p. FAINSTEIN, S. S. Cities and diversity: should we wa n t i t ? S h o u l d w e p l a n f o r i t ? U r b a n A f f a i r s Review, v. 41, n. 1, p. 3-19, 2005. http://dx.doi.org/ 10.1177/1078087405278968 FOLADORI, G. Sustentabilidad ambiental y contradicciones sociales. Ambiente & Sociedade, v. 5, n. 2, p. 19-34, 1999. FRASER, N. Reframing global justice. New Left Review, v. 36, p. 69-88, 2005. FRIEDMANN, J. The prospect of cities. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2002. FRIEDMANN, J. The good city: in defense of utopian thinking. International Journal of Urban and Regional Research, v. 24, n. 2, p. 460-472, 2000. http://dx.doi. org/10.1111/1468-2427.00258 FRIEDMANN, J. Planning in the public domain: from knowledge to action. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987. 229 p. GANDY, M. Concrete and clay: reworking nature in New York city. Cambridge: The MIT Press, 2002. GLOBE AWARD. Sustainable city award. Stockholm, 2014. Available at: . Accessed in: 28 Feb. 2014. KEIL, R. Progress report: urban political ecology. Urban Geography, v. 24, n. 8, p. 723-738, 2003. http://dx.doi. org/10.2747/0272-3638.24.8.723 KHOSLA, P. Privatization, segregation and dis- possession in western urban space: an antiracist, marxist-feminist reading of David Harvey. Toronto: York University, 2005. Available at: . Accessed in: 25 Nov. 2013. HALL, P. Good cities, better lives: how Europe discovered the lost art of urbanism. New York: Routlege, 2013. HARVEY, D. Social justice and the city. Athens: University of Georgia Press, 1973. HARVEY, D. The right to the city. New Left Review, v. 53, p. 23-40, 2008. H A RV E Y, D. T h e r i gh t to t h e c i t y. I n te r n a t i o n a l Journal of Urban and Regional Research, v. 27, n. 4, p. 939-941, 2003. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111 /j.0309-1317.2003.00492.x HARVEY, D. Justice, nature, and the geography of difference. Cambridge: Blackwell, 1996. HOUGH, M. Cities and natural process. New York: Routledge, 1995. urbe. Revista Brasileira de Gestão Urbana (Brazilian Journal of Urban Management), v. 6, n. 2, p. 158-169, maio/ago. 2014 Social Justice and the “Green” City 169 INTERNATIONAL COUNCIL FOR LOCAL ENVIRONMENTAL INITIATIVES – ICLEI. L ocal Governments for Sustainability. Green urban economy. Germany, 2013. Available at: . Accessed in: 25 Nov. 2013. LEFEBVRE, H. Le droit à la ville. Paris: Anthropos, 1968. 160 p. LIPSITZ, G. The possessive investment of whiteness: h o w wh i t e p e o p l e p ro i t f ro m i d e n t i t y p o l i t i c s . Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1998. 320 p. LUKE, T. W. Corporate social responsibility: an uneasy merger of sustainability and development. Sustainable Development, v. 21, n. 2, p. 83-91, 2013. http://dx.doi. org/10.1002/sd.1558 MARCUSE, P. Sustainability is not enough. Environment and urbanization, v. 10, n. 2, p. 103-111, 1998. http:// dx.doi.org/10.1177/095624789801000201 ORGANIC GARDENING. Green cities. Emmaus, 2014. Available at: . Accessed in: 28 Feb. 2014. POLÈSE, M.; STREN, R. The social sustainability of cities: diversity and the management of change. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2000. 384 p. REUTERS ENVIRONMENTAL FORUM. Top 5 greenest cities in the world. New York, 2010. Available at: . Accessed in: 28 Feb. 2014. ROGERS, H. The greening of capitalism? International Socialist Review, n. 70, 2009. Available at: . Accessed in: 25 Nov. 2013. SIEMENS. The green city index. Munich, 2012. Available at: . Accessed in: 28 Feb. 2014. SOJA, E. Postmodern geographies: the reassertion of space in critical social theory. New York: Verso, 1989. 228 p. VAN DER RYN, S.; COWAN, S. Ecological design. Washington: Island Press, 1996. W O R L D C O M M I S S I O N O N E N V I R O N M E N T A N D DEVELOPMENT. Our common future. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1987. 383 p. ZETTER, R.; WATSON, G. B. Designing sustainable cities in the developing world. Burlington: Ashgate, 2006. 210 p. ŽIŽEK, S. Slavoj Žižek on Starbucks and the delusion of green capitalism. Aol On, 2011. Available at: . Accessed in: 25 Nov. 2013. Recebido: 25/12/2013 Received: 12/25/2013 Aprovado: 10/03/2014 Approved: 03/10/2014 work_iyojaruqfjhdhpw7kxh26y34ym ---- Juha Räikkä, Social Justice in Practice This is a repository copy of Juha Räikkä, Social Justice in Practice. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/108568/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Lawford-Smith, H. (2016) Juha Räikkä, Social Justice in Practice. Journal of Value Inquiry, 50 (2). pp. 473-478. ISSN 0022-5363 https://doi.org/10.1007/s10790-014-9453-x eprints@whiterose.ac.uk https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ Reuse Unless indicated otherwise, fulltext items are protected by copyright with all rights reserved. The copyright exception in section 29 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 allows the making of a single copy solely for the purpose of non-commercial research or private study within the limits of fair dealing. The publisher or other rights-holder may allow further reproduction and re-use of this version - refer to the White Rose Research Online record for this item. Where records identify the publisher as the copyright holder, users can verify any specific terms of use on the publisher’s website. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing eprints@whiterose.ac.uk including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. mailto:eprints@whiterose.ac.uk https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ Juha Räikkä. Social Justice in Practice. Switzerland: Springer, 2014. ISBN 978-3-319-04633-4 £72.00 pb. Imagine yourself standing on the edge of a canyon, marveling at the terrain below, wondering about all the sights currently obscured from your view, and lamenting that you just don't have time to commit to the steep descent in and long trek across, which would give you a perspective from right up close. Being handed Juha Räikkä's new book Social Justice in Practice is like being told there's a fying fox you can take: the canyon is applied political theory, and the fying fox allows the reader to see many different issues, at some speed, and always with the wider context in view. Tuck your loose items of clothing away in your bags, and hop on. The book is loosely organized into six sections, with twelve chapters overall. The frst two sections ("Theory and Practice" and "Action and Uncertainty") introduce readers to the issues around the methodology of contemporary political theory, from whether the arguments of political theory should be more sensitive to what is feasible, through the correct weight to assign to citizens' political expectations that things will remain more or less the same, the bases of political reasoning about what is second-best when ideally preferred alternatives prove to be unavailable, and to what is taken as presumed (i.e. which side has the burden of proof) when it comes to political argumentation and political obligation. The third and sixth sections ("Unmasking Injustices" and "Self-Deception as Explanation") concern epistemic issues, including the acceptability of conspiracy theories, and self-deception for both religious and cultural reasons. The fourth section ("Privacy and Justice") concerns information broadly construed, in particular privacy and secrets, and the ffth section ("Morality and Inner Life") is about forgiveness and alien beliefs. The chapters are self-contained, so readers can feel free to either read the book from cover to cover, or to dip into different chapters as suits their interests. It would be impossible in a review-length piece to engage deeply with all twelve of the topics contained in Räikkä's book. I've chosen to focus in what follows on the parts of the book that I know best, to maximize the chance of saying something useful. So I'll restrict my attention to just two of the chapters, which are, respectively, "Social Justice in Practice", and "How to Find the Second-Best Option" (noting, for the record, that I found "The Dilemma of Conservative Justice"―wedged between these two―especially interesting and useful). Readers interested in, or more familiar with, the book's later topics are encouraged to consult the book directly. In recent years there has been some backlash against the utopianism of much contemporary political theory, which has taken the form of increased discussion about the distinction between ideal and non-ideal theory and the proper place of each within political theory as a discipline. Some think ideal theory has no place at all, because we should be solving the problems we actually have rather than constructing perfect theoretical worlds in which those problems are abstracted away from; some think non-ideal theory has no place at all, because it involves unacceptable concessions to the status quo. The claim that political theory needs a greater proportion of feasibility-constrained arguments weighs in on the non-ideal side of this debate. It doesn't entail that this is the right kind or the only kind of political theorizing; just that it's important, both for evaluating the current political order, and for shifting to a better one, that we take certain constraints as fxed and think about the improvements we can make in spite of them. In Chapter 1, "Social Justice in Practice", Räikkä argues that feasibility arguments are of most beneft to those who in fact cannot make use of them, and that given his view of the role of political theory, it's just not true that political theory needs a greater proportion of feasibility-constrained arguments. Let me explain each of these claims, before commenting on what I think is mistaken about them. The frst claim, about beneft, is that in political life, a claim that some outcome is infeasible and therefore we should pursue an alternative course of action will often be benefcial to those who, by their actions, actually make the outcome infeasible. Räikkä gives many examples, including: the people of a country who claim that the government's improving public health by prohibiting the consumption of alcohol would result in a black market for liquor; the talented, who claim that without suffcient economic rewards they would not be motivated to exercise those talents for the beneft of the greater society; nurses, who claim that without increased wages they'll emigrate to countries where the pay is better; religious groups, claiming that if ritual slaughter of animals is prohibited it will simply be outsourced to the black market where it will likely involve even more suffering for the animals; and parents of sick children, who claim that if the government decreases its subsidies of the required medicines they'll turn to less safe but cheaper alternatives online. In each case, the people making the claims about what outcomes would follow if certain measures were implemented are themselves responsible for producing those outcomes. People could obey a law prohibiting alcohol, the talented could take talent as its own reward, nurses could work for comparatively low wages, religious groups could stop slaughtering animals, and parents could simply spend more on medicines. But feasibility arguments are agent-relative; they explicitly exclude 'self-prediction'. I can't say "it's infeasible that I write this review of Räikkä's book, because I'm going to watch another episode of The Killing instead" (the hidden premise being that I ought to write the review only if it's suffciently feasible that I do). Many analyses of feasibility assume the trying of the relevant agent, so they would say my writing the review is feasible if I would be suffciently likely to write it, so long as I tried. But of course, if I tried I'd likely succeed, so writing the review is not infeasible for me after all. But the citizens, the talented, the nurses, the religious, and the parents in Räikkä's examples are all in that position, so while they'd do well out of having their claims about infeasibility accepted (in gaining concessions by government), they're in fact not in a position to make those claims. Infeasibility is no excuse for those whose actions cause it. Those arguments, then, are really just threats in disguise: the nurses are saying that if the government doesn't raise their wages, they'll leave the country. Räikkä's second claim relies on the role of political theory being to inform public debate over political issues. Accepting for the moment that this is its role (I do not think it is and will soon explain why), his claim is that the overall message political theorists give the public should be "be better", rather than "give in to threats". A nice example of this choice is featuring in the news and across social media at the moment: nail polish that detects rape drugs in beverages. The nail polish is clearly a non-ideal solution, because it takes the prevalence of attempted drugging for granted, and it looks to protect potential victims by giving them a way to detect the presence of the drugs in their drinks. Many commentators are angry about the invention, because they think it sends the wrong message, namely that it's the responsibility of the potential victim to ensure she isn't raped (to wear the nail polish, to check her drinks) rather than the responsibility of the would-be rapists not to rape. If political theorists were to have the opportunity to weigh in on this debate, they should be giving "ideal" argumentation, namely about the wrongness of rape, the importance of enthusiastic consent, about gender-egalitarianism, and about mutual respect; not "feasibility-constrained" argumentation, conceding that the world is a place with rape in it, and advising women to protect themselves as best they can (or others to protect potential victims as best they can, including by coming up with these kinds of inventions). In Räikkä's view, the role of political theory is to inform public debate, and this should be done by sending the clear, "ideal" message: which in this case would be that it is the responsibility of men not to rape. So much for the main claims of the chapter; now to the problems with them, taking the latter claim frst. While one role of political theory may well be to weigh in on public political debate, that is surely not its only role. Political Theory is a sub- area of Philosophy, and philosophical inquiry is broadly-speaking the pursuit of truth. It determines both evaluative truths (truths about what is good, whether or not it can ever be actual) and normative truths (truths about what we should attempt to bring about). Setting aside the evaluative truths, the normative truths may be unconditional (ought p) or conditional (given that not-p, ought q). The following two claims are not mutually exclusive: would-be rapists ought not to rape, and, given that at least some would-be rapists will in fact rape, victims ought to be protected as much as possible from potential attack. We can lament the fact that our circumstances are such that the latter is true―I'm sure we would all agree that we'd much rather be in a world in which anti- rape drug nail polish were not a useful invention. (Whether the nail polish is an effective and not overly demanding means of protection is an empirical question). Whether a political theorist wants to make an unconditional, "ideal" claim, or a conditional, "feasibility-constrained" claim, depends on the kind of project she is interested in, and wanting to weigh in on public debate does not determine that she make only the former types of claims. Taking Räikkä's side in this debate has the advantage of avoiding any accusation of victim-blaming, because it avoids giving any responsibilities at all to those who might either use the nail polish, or who might create the nail polish or other similar inventions, and therefore avoids blaming them if they fail to act on those responsibilities (which would indeed be a despicable implication in the case of the victim: we certainly do not want to say that a person who fails to wear the nail polish is in any sense at all responsible for her situation if she is attacked). But going in for feasibility-constrained recommendations has the advantage of not restricting moral advice to contexts in which there is no wrongdoing. Even if the reader disagrees over the diagnosis of the nail polish case, there are many other cases in which we want to know what the good worlds look like given that certain wrongs will remain in place, or at least not be completely eradicated). Returning to the frst claim, this makes a serious mistake in understanding agent-relativity. Feasibility assessments do not permit of self-prediction, but in none of the examples Räikkä used was there something resembling a "self"―either an individual self or collective agent―whose actions were being predicted. He acknowledges this, to some extent, when he says "to assume that nurses could decide not to emigrate... is not to assume that there is a strictly organized collective agent", but it's not merely that there is no "strictly organized" collective. There are only uncoordinated aggregates of persons: citizens of a country, those with talent, nurses, those in a certain religious group, parents. Perhaps there are cases, such as when nurses are represented by strong and cohesive labour unions, or when religious groups are coordinated within one church, where the groups can act on (the functional equivalents of) intentions, and thereby count as a single unit for the purposes of assessing feasibility. Parents, those with talent, and most likely citizens, do not count in this way. Thus the claim that those who would most beneft from infeasibility arguments cannot make use of them falls down. Assessments of what is feasible, and how our normative recommendations ought to be adjusted in light of what is feasible and what isn't, are usually made by political theorists, political analysts and commentators, policy advisors, those in government. Those people can all make predictions about what will happen if certain measures are implemented, such as making the consumption of alcohol illegal, or refusing to raise nurses' wages. They might well reason that on balance, a future in which nurses simply accept low pay without being incentivized to emigrate by neighbouring countries' higher wages is infeasible, and give a feasibility- constrained argument (holding this fact fxed) that it is better to swallow the costs of raising wages than the costs of large-scale emigration of nurses. Räikkä does not deny that this is possible, but he greatly understates the extent to which this is the primary use of feasibility-constrained argumentation, and the use to which many working on feasibility envisage it being put to. In Chapter 3, "How to Find the Second-Best Option", Räikkä makes a helpful distinction between three different ways in which we might approximate when our political "bests" are out of reach. He calls these "condition", "degree" and "denial". Condition-based approximation tells us to get as many of the things that matter as we can. Degree-based approximation tells us to get as much of each of the things that matter as we can. And denial-based approximation tells us to go for the ideal even when we know it won't quite be realized, because what we'll get will probably be close enough to be an adequate approximation What's great about this chapter is that it doesn't make the same mistake as quite a bit of the discussion of second-bests in political theory by following the economic results and assuming the interdependence of the desirable elements of the "best". Values are independent: it's just not true that fnding one to be out of reach we should revise our whole conception of what we're aiming for. To put these different methods of approximation in terms of a political case, imagine that the case for Scottish Independence is strong on the grounds of community, security, and self- determination. And now imagine that our best empirical predictions tell us that we just cannot get an independent Scotland that is fully self-determining, while also fully secure and fully embodying community. Assuming these three values to have equal weight, the condition-based approach would tell us to take whichever two we liked (3/3 conditions is best, but 2/3 conditions beats 1/3); the degree-based approach would tell us to get as much self-determination, security and community as we can (any confguration with some of each value instantiated beats any confguration in which one value remains entirely uninstantiated); and the denial-based approach tells us to just go ahead with whatever the original plan was, assuming things will work out as "close enough". There are two problems with the discussion in this chapter. The frst is that the example Räikkä uses (about where to take a holiday) is unhelpfully apolitical, and misleading in the case of the degree-based conception. The problems with getting "more rather than less" of a value are put in geographical terms, and give the wrong results for that reason, because getting closer to a holiday destination (and ending up somewhere in the ocean) is quite obviously not better than going somewhere else entirely. But a more sophisticated understanding of the metric of degrees ―which is to say, what counts as more or less of something―will avoid this problem. Approximating a relaxing holiday in the sunshine might take you geographically far afeld from the original destination, just as approximating comprehensive security, community, and self-determination in an independent Scotland might take you politically far afeld from the utopian vision of independence. If the scale is specifed well, the imperative to get more rather than less doesn't look nearly as problematic. Räikkä's argument in the chapter is that real people when making decisions about approximation don't actually rely on any of these three theoretical versions of approximating, and therefore those versions can't be criticized on the grounds that they cause poor decision-making. Even if the outcomes of their decisions often align with the outcomes any one such procedure would yield, that is not a reason to be critical of that procedure. He takes this to make the three theoretical versions of approximation immune from empirical rejection. However, what he doesn't comment on is which of the three is in fact theoretically the most well-motivated, or has the greatest advantages over the others. The denial-based approach looks obviously inappropriate, yet little is made of this. Perhaps his aim was only to insulate practice from theory (and vice versa), but having made these useful distinctions between the ways in which approximating might be done, it was somewhat unsatisfying that more was not said about how second-best theorizing ought to go, and what the right relationship between such theory and practice might look like. Holly Lawford-Smith University of Sheffeld work_iz66yxofdfartnanworlyffy4a ---- Climate justice in a carbon budget  Article  Accepted Version  McKinnon, C. (2015) Climate justice in a carbon budget.  Climatic Change, 133 (3). pp. 375­384. ISSN 0165­0009 doi:  https://doi.org/10.1007/s10584­015­1382­6 Available at  http://centaur.reading.ac.uk/40496/  It is advisable to refer to the publisher’s version if you intend to cite from the  work.  See Guidance on citing  . To link to this article DOI: http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10584­015­1382­6  Publisher: Springer  All outputs in CentAUR are protected by Intellectual Property Rights law,  including copyright law. Copyright and IPR is retained by the creators or other  copyright holders. Terms and conditions for use of this material are defined in  the End User Agreement  .  www.reading.ac.uk/centaur    CentAUR  Central Archive at the University of Reading  Reading’s research outputs online http://centaur.reading.ac.uk/71187/10/CentAUR%20citing%20guide.pdf http://www.reading.ac.uk/centaur http://centaur.reading.ac.uk/licence 1 Climate Justice in a Carbon Budget Catriona McKinnon Department of Politics and International Relations University of Reading Whiteknights Reading RG6 6AA United Kingdom c.mckinnon@reading.ac.uk +44 (0) 118 387 8502 Institute of Climate Change and Public Policy Nanjing University of Information Science and Technology (NUIST) 219 Ningliu Road, Pukou District Jiangsu Province 210044 China Author biog: Catriona McKinnon is Professor of Political Theory, and Director of the Leverhulme Programme in Climate Justice, at the University of Reading. She is the author of Climate Change and Future Justice: Precaution, Compensation, Triage (Routledge 2011), and co-editor of Climate Change and Liberal Priorities (Routledge, 2012) and of The Ethics of Climate Governance (Rowman and Littlefield, forthcoming). She is currently writing a book about climate justice and international criminal law. mailto:c.mckinnon@reading.ac.uk 2 3 Abstract The fact of a carbon budget given commitment to limiting global-mean temperature increase to below 2°C warming relative to pre-industrial levels makes CO2 emissions a scarce resource. This fact has significant consequences for the ethics of climate change. The paper highlights some of these consequences with respect to (a) applying principles of distributive justice to the allocation of rights to emissions and the costs of mitigation and adaptation, (b) compensation for the harms and risks of climate change, (c) radical new ideas about a place for criminal justice in tackling climate change, and (d) catastrophe ethics. Keywords: carbon budget; climate ethics; intergenerational justice; distributive justice; compensation; criminal justice; catastrophe ethics. Climate Justice in a Carbon Budget In their paper Knutti and Rogelj lay out fourteen facts supported by climate science showing CO2 emissions to be a scarce resource, given commitment to limiting global-mean temperature increase to below 2°C warming relative to pre- industrial levels. These facts raise questions that require answers informed by ethics and political philosophy and – further on – the social sciences, in the search for feasible processes and institutions of equitable and effective climate governance. In this paper I shall lay out a roadmap of approaches to climate justice given how the fact of the carbon budget brings future people within the scope of theories of climate justice. The roadmap will start with an outline of some well established approaches informed by distributive justice. Assuming that we can settle on a just allocation of emissions and costs that properly takes account of the claims of both present and future people, further questions of justice are raised given the carbon budget. First, what do those who exceed their allocation, or who fail to meet costs rightly assigned to them, owe to innocent people affected by these 4 failures? Standardly, principles of corrective justice guide thinking about who owes what to whom when things go wrong in ways such as this, at any given point in time. The roadmap in the paper will highlight a new way in which these principles are fit to guide thinking about failures in the face of the carbon budget: that present people are liable to provide resources enabling satisfaction of possible compensation claims made by future people put at risk of harm by the failures of those present people. The second question of justice raised by failures to do what justice demands in the face of the carbon budget takes the roadmap into entirely new territory. When people act contrary to what is required by justice in ways that risk catastrophic consequences for innocent others, despite knowledge of the risks they create through their conduct, principles of criminal justice are activated. The paper will indicate a place of for criminal justice in the pantheon of our ethically informed approaches to climate change in the face of the carbon budget. The facts identified by Knutti and Rogelj are as follows. 1. CO2 longevity: a large fraction of CO2 emitted stays in the atmosphere for centuries and longer. 2. The future effects of CO2 emissions are uncertain, and a large fraction of climate change caused by these emissions is irreversible insofar as that CO2 is not actively removed from the atmosphere. 3. The real warming commitment is the inertia of present infrastructures and practices which are not changing so as to reduce global CO2 emissions. 4. Every ton of CO2 emitted causes further warming. 5. The causal contribution made by countries and generations to past and future climate change is approximately in proportion to their total cumulative emissions. 6. Two thirds of the total CO2 budget in line with a 2°C warming limit has already been emitted; at current emission rates, the budget will be depleted in around 30 years. 5 7. There is a surplus of CO2 available in fossil fuel resources beyond the budget, which means that some carbon will have to remain in the ground, or be sequestered, in order to stay within the carbon budget. 8. There is uncertainty about the exact size of the carbon budget. 9. There have been great historical inequalities between countries in their cumulative CO2 emissions, and in the distribution of the benefits created by emissions. 10. Taking into account all drivers of climate change, historical contributions to it are very unevenly distributed over countries. 11. Achieving emissions reductions to remain within the carbon budget is a global collective action problem. 12. Present delays in mitigation efforts create greater mitigation burdens for subsequent generations. 13. Delays in mitigation are commonly justified by reference to a social discount rate. The choice of a social discount rate is an ethical choice reflecting the way in which future generations are valued by the current generation. 14. Geoengineering under a climate emergency also requires equitable solutions in theory and in practice. Given how anthropogenic CO2 emissions do not remain at source but rather mingle evenly through the atmosphere, and given how climate change will damage (indeed– and is already causing – damage to the planet as a habitat for human beings (let alone other species), the fact that there is a carbon budget and that it is quickly being depleted (facts 4 and 6) brings climate change within the purview of philosophical theories of justice. In the context of a carbon budget the questions addressed by different families of (interconnected) theories are as follows. (1) Distributive justice: ensure patterns of distribution of a moderately scarce good such that the benefits delivered by the good, and the burdens involved in maintaining the pattern, are justly shared by all parties in the 6 distribution.1 Given a carbon budget, in present circumstances, the good to be distributed is emissions allocations and the burdens to be distributed are the costs created by mitigation and adaptation programmes. There are two things worth noting here. First, given that we will ultimately have to move to a zero carbon economy, emissions allocations will at some point transform from being a moderately scarce good to being an extremely scarce good (perhaps sooner than we think). In these circumstances it is not clear that principles of distributive justice continue to apply to emissions allocations. Second, following Henry Shue, what really matters from a moral point of view is that human energy needs are met (especially those of the global poor), and it is only contingently the case that emissions allocations do this (Shue 2013). These needs could be met by non carbon based energy production. Thus in a decarbonised global economy questions of distributive justice will still exist but will be refocused on the allocation of access to non-carbon based energy sources so as to ensure justice in the distribution of the benefits of this access and the costs of providing and maintaining it. (2) Corrective justice: ensure that wrongs done are repaired. Theories of corrective justice contain principles of liability to connect those causing wrongful harm with those they harm in ways fit to support claims for compensation by the latter.2 In the context of a carbon budget, those who exceed their emissions allocations and/or fail to bear the costs of mitigation and adaptation that are rightfully theirs, are prima facie liable to provide compensation to innocent people suffering climate-related harmed as a result. Cases in tort law with this character are appearing in law courts with increasing frequency (Adam 2011). It is worth noting that although most accounts of liability under corrective justice specify negligence as a mens rea, not all do, and not for every tort. If liability for 1 In modern times, the most famous theory of this type is John Rawls’ ‘justice as fairness’ (Rawls 1971). Thinking about distributive justice from a philosophical perspective has a long history, and much contemporary political philosophy (at least in the Anglo-American tradition) is concerned with questions of distributive justice. 2 An important book in this field is Coleman 1992. 7 climate-related harms is strict - that is, if it does not depend on arguing that the defendant ought to have known the risks of climate related harm created by emissions - then excuses related to supposed uncertainty in climate science become irrelevant. (3) Criminal justice: ensure the fair prosecution, trial and punishment of those who commit public wrongs.3 There is disagreement in theories of criminal justice about the purpose of punishment: retribution, deterrence, and the communication of fundamental norms of behaviour for a given community are all candidates. Thus far in the literature on climate justice, criminal justice has played no role. Later on in the paper I shall indicate a role it should play. From the point of view of justice the picture is complicated by facts (1, 2, 8, 9, 10, 12 and 13) about the length of time CO2 remains in the Earth’s atmosphere and thereby affects the climate. These facts make questions about justice in a carbon budget essentially intergenerational as well as intragenerational: members of any current temporal cohort in the community of humanity are capable of significantly and permanently damaging conditions of life for members of temporal cohorts not yet born, who are seriously vulnerable to the conduct of those who precede them, because time’s arrow points in one direction only. Of course, it has always been the case that the past shapes the present and future. But the dawn of the Anthropocene has been marked by an unprecedented change to this feature of the human condition: scientific, technological, and industrial advances make most recent generations (at least in more developed countries) more powerful with respect to the future than has ever been true of any generation in human history.4 The facts about the atmospheric lifetime of CO2 combined with facts about the carbon budget make it necessary to think about climate justice from an intergenerational point of view. One influential account of the demands of intergenerational justice is given by John Rawls: 3 The philosophy of criminal justice is enjoying a renaissance at present. One could do no better than to start with Duff 2009. 4 The term ‘Anthropocene’ refers to a new epoch in the Earth’s history in which human activity is, for the first time, having a significant global impact. See Crutzen and Stoermer 2000. 8 intergenerational justice requires that social cooperation within any temporal cohort meets standards that any generation in time would have wanted all generations prior to it to have adopted and followed, and would want all generations subsequent to it to adopt and follow (Rawls 1993). Crudely, any generation ought to save and conserve in ways it would want every generation to save and conserve.5 If we combine a commitment to intergenerational justice with the philosophical theories of justice outlined above, what are the implications for life under a carbon budget? With respect to distributive justice the first question is: what is a fair distribution of emissions allocations now given a requirement to ensure that future people are able to meet their energy needs? One prominent proposal is that emissions rights be given an equal distribution across all people, given the plausible claim that all people have equal rights to means enabling them to satisfy their energy needs (Jamieson 2005; Vanderheiden 2008; Singer 2002). One way to calculate equal per capita allocations would be to divide the amount of carbon remaining in the budget by the number of people currently alive. This is clearly flawed. First, it makes no provision for transition to non-carbon energy sources within the lifetimes of presently existing people; effectively, it would permit people in the current time slice to blow the carbon budget entirely leaving them with no means by which to satisfy their own future energy needs. (Of course, in this scenario, people would just continue to use carbon-based energy and blow the budget even more). Second, the proposal takes no account of the energy needs of future people. Consider how emissions allocations within a carbon budget would look if 1) a very large number of people will exist in the future and 2) all those future people’s energy needs will require carbon intensive energy in order to be satisfied. If 1) and 2) are true then the fixed amount of carbon remaining in the budget (as Knutti and Rogelj make clear) has to be divided by a much larger 5 Rawls uses his famous ‘veil of ignorance’ to justify this principle as the one any person would choose if they did not know the particular generation to which they belong. For Rawls, this models the irrelevance of temporal location to any person’s status as a being deserving of justice. Note that the claim does not imply that all generations are required to save at a uniform rate for the sake of later generations. (Rawls 1993). 9 number of people than if we attended only to the carbon-based energy needs of present people. And this generates highly negative emissions allocations for present people. What this suggests is that if people in the present are to allocate equal rights to emissions with a positive value to present people, an equal per capita approach - insofar as it is justified by reference to the equal satisfaction of all persons’ energy needs - commits them to the development of non-carbon based energy technologies that will ensure that future people’s energy needs are as well satisfied as those of present people.6 The fact of the carbon budget means that ultimately total global emissions must reduce to zero: all moral arguments about climate change must be sensitive to this. This means that whatever initial distribution of rights to emissions allocations is justified there will come a point – sooner rather than later – at which these rights are trumped by the fact that the carbon budget is close to depletion. The moral parameters created by the fact of the carbon budget are evident in ethical arguments for differential emissions reductions pathways for different countries that, over time, converge to achieve the total reductions necessary to remain within the budget. They are also evident in arguments for the rapid development of zero carbon energy technologies, assuming that people have a basic human right to subsistence which cannot be met without development (Shue 1980). At present, most development is carbon intensive, and involves the creation of ‘subsistence emissions’ (Shue 1993). But such emissions are, as Shue puts it, an ‘avoidable necessity’ (Shue 1995)(as reflected in fact 3): they are necessary for people in developing economies to achieve the subsistence to which they have a basic human right, but this right could be met just as well (perhaps better?) by zero carbon development. Taking seriously the basic human right to subsistence in the face of the carbon budget makes it morally urgent to secure the energy needs of world’s poor through low - ultimately, and soon, zero - carbon development (Shue 2013). 6 An extended discussion of the equal per capita view, and other issues related to distributive justice in the allocation of emissions see Caney 2012. 10 This leads to the second question of distributive justice: what is a just distribution of the costs of mitigating and adapting to climate change, and of the development and implementation of zero-carbon energy technologies, within a carbon budget? Two key principles have received much attention. First, ‘polluter pays’: those who have contributed most to the problem are those who ought to bear the greatest burdens in addressing it. Given facts 9 and 10, the polluter pays principle would allocate higher absolute emissions reductions targets to countries in a more advanced state of development in virtue of their historically disproportionate emissions. But there are problems here. In particular, a temporal cohort in the Anthropocene located within a more developed country might object that they are being required to bear heavy burdens as a result of conduct not their own, for which they could not be held responsible, viz. the conduct of long dead countrymen who undertook development using fossil fuels. This temporal cohort might reasonably argue that any principle of justice governing relations between people across time must not impose burdens on those not responsible for causing the problem being addressed by the burdensome requirement. A different approach which does not allocate burdensome requirements to address a problem by reference to causal contribution to the problem is the ‘beneficiary pays’ principle: those who have benefited from conduct causing the problem are those who ought to bear the costs of solving the problem, even when they have not caused the problem at all. According to this principle, people in more developed countries have benefited massively from their predecessors’ emissions, and this is sufficient to require them to make higher emissions reductions (or to contribute more to global emissions reductions, if past development generated by fossil fuel has been replaced by relatively low carbon development). This approach requires a reliable method for identifying and measuring present benefits generated by past emissions. This is a challenge both from a causal perspective (to what extent can clear chains of causation linking present benefits to past emissions be disentangled from other causal chains?), 11 and from a normative perspective (according to what theory of value does a change in a person’s, or group’s, conditions qualify as a benefit?).7 Furthermore, objections to this approach have, as with objections to the polluter pays approach, focused on the fairness of requiring people who are not responsible for a problem to bear the greatest costs associated with tackling it. Imagine that you go away on a three-month trip, and when you return you find that an uninvited skilful gardener has cultivated a flourishing vegetable patch in an unused bed in your garden, and that she died shortly thereafter, and before your return. You enjoy eating the vegetables, and your health is benefited. In cultivating the patch the gardener made liberal use of the village fertiliser stored in the barn, without realising that the supply is limited. Your neighbours, who have also been away on a three month trip, are now trying to get their vegetable patches established. On seeing your abundant crop, and learning of how it came about, they might make the following demands of you: (i) that you stop using any more of the limited supply of fertiliser; (ii) that you share your vegetable bounty with them, given that its existence is entirely dependent on the mystery gardener having used a disproportionate share of the fertiliser; and (iii) that you work hard with them to find new vegetable growing techniques that do not rely on fertiliser, given that it is fast running out. Advocates of the beneficiary pays principle must explain why your unrequested, but welcome, receipt of the vegetables generates an enforceable and non voluntary requirement for you to comply with some or all of demands (i)-(iii).8 And they must unpack the analogy in a convincing way. Eating freshly grown vegetables has clear, measurable 7 A promising approach to these questions draws on Sen and Nussbaum’s ‘capabilities’ approach (Sen 1992). On this view, what matters, from a political point of view, for the assessment of advantage is not levels of welfare enjoyed, or amounts of resources owned or controlled, but rather the extent to which people are free to achieve well being, understood in terms of objective opportunities to do, and become, what they have reason to value. 8 Most people would think it would be very generous of you to act in the ways specified by the demands, but given the unreliability of generosity as a motive - especially when the sacrifices involved relate to all the comforts and pleasures of living in a more developed country - what we really want are arguments to show that you can legitimately be compelled to make the sacrifices required to meet the demands. 12 benefits for health. How do the products of carbon intensive development benefit people? In general, Knutti and Rogelj note throughout their paper that climate change is a wicked problem. The global collective action needed to tackle it (fact 11), the uncertainty about the future effects of CO2 emissions (fact 2) and about the exact size of the carbon budget (fact 8), the possibility of climate catastrophes and the geoengineering agenda they would foreground (fact 14), and the difficulty of thinking through – from a moral and policy perspective – how to balance the rights and interests of present people against the rights and interests of future people (fact 13) all combine to make climate change a problem unprecedented in the history of ethics. A number of prominent climate ethicists have reflected on this. For example, Dale Jamieson argues that our existing ethical theories are inadequate to this unprecedented problem (Jamieson 2014). And Stephen Gardiner argues that the structure of the climate problem renders it a ‘perfect moral storm’ that presents the global rich and powerful in the present generation with various temptations to moral corruption; that is, to forms of argument and conduct that enable the global rich and powerful to continue to pursue their own interests while claiming to be (and perhaps even believing that they are) promoting climate justice (Gardiner 2011).9 This could have disastrous consequences for the world’s poor, and for future people. Of particular salience here is his account of ‘intergenerational buck passing’ in climate policy-making, which amplifies fact 12: given a carbon budget, ineffective action on emissions reductions now creates a bigger emissions reductions burden for future people (Rogelj et al 2013). The temptation to pass the emissions reductions buck on to future generations may iterate down through subsequent generations, greatly enhancing the risk of climate catastrophe. And any generation in a state of climate emergency may reasonably react by burning more fossil fuels in an attempt to provide support and assistance to members of its cohort experiencing that emergency, which will then make the climate problem even worse for 9 He analyses the Kyoto Protocol in exactly these terms. 13 subsequent generations who may react in a similar way, etc. Intergenerational buck passing may, Gardiner argues, create an intergenerational arms race.10 The demandingness of what we owe to future people in the face of present and past emissions is diluted in climate policy by the use of a social discount rate in calculating the costs of climate policies. The social discount rate places considerations of the costs of climate change to many future people outside the scope of policy. It does this by specifying a certain point in time (determined by the value of the discount rate) beyond which all costs approach zero. Use of a social discount rate in future oriented policy-making is ubiquitous in economic approaches. But the very choice to use a discount rate at all is a moral choice: it represents a decision to undertake a weighing of the interests of more distant future people against those of present people and less distant future people so as to prioritise the latter categories over the former. And weighing interests in this way, regardless of the temporal location of the interest holders, is a moral undertaking (fact 13. That is not to say that all forms of weighing are morally prohibited; perhaps there are good ethical reasons for committing to some forms of discounting (for example, of the commodities that future people will possess) and for rejecting others (for example, of future persons’ well being) (Broome 2012). Furthermore, the value that is given to the discount rate is a way of representing the weight to be given to the interests of distant future people in present policy making, and so is an ethical choice in need of justification going well beyond mere reference to the present market interest rate (Broome 2012). Moral and political philosophers have been alive to these issues as economic approaches have ascended to the dominance they have presently and climate ethicists continue to resist the presentation of the discount rate as a value neutral and innocuous part of the toolkit of cost benefit analysis (Parfit 1992; Broome 1994; Ackerman 2008; Jamieson 2014; Gardiner 2011). 10 Gardiner argues that geoengineering presents significant opportunities for morally corrupt intergenerational buck passing. It enables the geoengineering generation to tell themselves that they are making a ‘morally serious choice’ by doing this instead of reducing emissions, when the reality is that the geoengineering generation will probably not have to bear any of the risks of implementing the technology, and will have increased the emissions reductions burden for subsequent generations (Gardiner 2011, 364). 14 Debates about intergenerational distributive justice in the face of climate change conceptualise the Earth’s absorptive capacity with respect to CO2 (up to the cap expressed in the carbon budget) as a good in need of fair distribution across all generations (which means, in effect, fair distribution across present and future generations, given that past emissions are unalterable). However, this way of thinking about the atmosphere has implications beyond distributive justice, for two other domains of justice that are well established in political philosophy: corrective justice, and criminal justice. The commitment central to corrective justice is: repair wrongs done. Corrective justice requires that any party suffering wrongful harm as a result of the conduct of another has a justified claim of rectification which ought to be met by the harmer; most commonly, through the provision of compensation to the victim by the harmer (Coleman 1992). Demands for compensation in the name of corrective justice are now regularly made in the intragenerational context, and are likely to proliferate as the impacts of climate change worsen (Farber 2008; Hunter and Salzman 2007). However, corrective justice can also have intergenerational scope: it can connect members of the present generation to as yet unborn future people in a relationship of liability for reparation, and this has significant consequences for what present people owe to future people given the fact of a carbon budget. Under corrective justice in the intragenerational context, an agent becomes liable for providing compensation only when what she does causes harm: prior to the causation of harm, there is no liability. However, there are good reasons to think that liability under corrective justice ought also to respond to the imposition of impermissible risk. Here, we can think of an agent imposing impermissible risk as ipso facto liable for providing the means for compensation which can be accessed by any future people for whom the risk ripens into a harm (McKinnon 2011). With respect to climate justice, this interpretation of corrective justice enables us to claim that insofar as its CO2 emissions create impermissible risks for future people, the present generation is required to make provision for the 15 compensation that will be owed to future people if the risks the present generation is imposing mature into harms for those people. Given the fact of a carbon budget, the present generation’s failure to date to radically reduce global CO2 emissions imposes impermissible risks on future people; the harmful consequences for future people of business-as-usual are well documented. In addition, and not sufficiently well noted, is the way in which the risks being imposed on future people by present people not only relate to basic human rights, but also to future people’s capacities to act ethically with respect to the people who will follow them (fact 12). By passing the CO2 emissions reduction buck to future people, we might – as Gardiner notes – blight their lives by putting them in a position wherein whatever they do, they will do wrong (Gardiner 2011: 389). There are well founded worries about how compensation schemes for climate change harms and risks could function in practice so as to distribute ‘permits to pollute’: so long as an agent is willing and able to provide for compensation for those harmed by the climate change caused by their emissions, they may continue with business as usual. Crudely, the global rich get to continue as they are.11 What these worries make clear is that any set of principles of intergenerational climate justice must contain principles that prohibit certain types and rates of emissions, and activity fit to exacerbate these emissions, regardless of the willingness and ability of the emitter to provide compensation. These prohibitions will be set by reference to the carbon budget, and the ideal distribution of emissions allowances across generations, given progression towards a zero carbon global economy in order to remain within the budget. Given the importance to the temporally extended political community of humanity of not exceeding this budget, these prohibitions have great moral significance for all generations. The domain of justice concerned with the commission of ‘public wrongs’ – that is, conduct violating standards of the greatest moral significance to any community – is criminal justice. Could philosophical theories of criminal justice be brought to bear in the context of he carbon budget? 11 These worries also apply to offsetting schemes (Hyams and Fawcett 2013). 16 The only attempt in the literature to do this is my work-in-progress on using international criminal law to address reckless conduct that creates risks of human extinction. I call this a law of ‘postericide’.12 This work develops arguments for the idea that a new international crime of postericide is a morally required response to humanity's changed circumstances in the Anthropocene, given the carbon budget. Postericide is: Intentional or reckless conduct systematically and seriously threatening the extinction – or near extinction – of humanity. International criminal law contains no precedents for the prosecution of postericide. But, I argue, the normative commitments at the heart of international criminal law commit us to revising it in ways that make it fit for human life in the Anthropocene. Here in the Anthropocene it is in our power to permanently damage or destroy conditions on Earth for all those who will live after us. Now consider the following conception of international criminal law. In an international context we are accountable to one another as human political animals. When a state fails to do what it ought to do for us qua political animals – when it fails to perform the functions according to which its existence is justified, i.e. the delivery of justice – then our shared membership of the community of human political animals generates the following responsibilities. First, a responsibility to those who are affected by their state’s abuse of its powers, or its failure to offer them protection from attack by others; that is, a responsibility to victims of international crimes. And second, a responsibility to those who commit these crimes – whether they be agents of the state, or independent agents acting in the vacuum of a failed state – to use international criminal law to 12 McKinnon, ‘Climate Change as Postericide’, Leverhulme Trust Research Fellowship 2014-16, grant number RF-2014-021/8. 17 prosecute them.13 Here, international criminal law is a declaration of our commitment as members of the community of human political animals to protect the institutional conditions we need to live well together. It is now a short (but certainly not uncontroversial) step to the conclusion that international criminal law ought to govern present conduct insofar as it creates serious and systematic extinction risks. The reason for this is we are in political community with future people. Taking seriously the idea of international criminal law as an expression of what human beings owe to one another regardless of their location in space, this body of law ought also to protect all human beings regardless of their location in time. Given the carbon budget, if groups in the presently existing temporal cohort egregiously exceed their allocations and do not make concentrated and resolute efforts to develop zero carbon energy technologies, and if they are aware of the extinction risks their conduct creates, then they are liable for postericide. Who might these groups be? Fossil fuel companies and states obstructing meaningful action on climate change are the obvious candidates. Summing up, the facts foregrounded by Knutti and Rogelj have great significance for debates about what we owe to one another, and to future people, in the name of justice. In particular, the fact of the carbon budget, and the uncertainty surrounding its value and the consequences of exceeding it, bring present CO2 emissions within the scope of pedigreed debates about justice now being extended to generate obligations to future people. These obligations are, without exception, extremely demanding; and the structure of the climate change problem presents people here and now – in this crucial moment in history (fact 6) – with many tempting opportunities to duck these obligations by continuing to emit à la business as usual (fact 3, fact 7). One way this is sometimes attempted is with spurious claims that the science does not support the assumptions forming the background against which justice based arguments are made. Another route to inaction that refers to climate science cites the substantial uncertainties about the carbon budget (fact 8) - what it is, how much 13 This line of argument draws on ideas in Luban 2004 and Duff 2010. 18 is left, etc. - as justifying political inaction with respect to local and global emissions reductions. This is clearly not justified from an ethical point of view. On the contrary - as Knutti and Rogelj insist, and for a range of reasons delivered by ethically informed reflection on the implications of depleting the carbon budget - our continuing uncertainty provides us with more, not fewer, urgent reasons to act to reduce global emissions. To end, let me reflect upon the direction of travel that philosophical thinking about justice might have to take if we deplete the carbon budget. Although there is no certainty about this (fact 2), the atmospheric lifetime of CO2 (fact 1) and its contribution to continued warming regardless of what point in history any ton of it is emitted (fact 4) means that business as usual puts future people at risk of catastrophic climate change, creating an extreme scarcity of resources necessary for survival at local, and possibly global, scales. Contemporary theories of justice, and their ancestors in the Anglo-American tradition, work with a background assumption of moderate scarcity only: few enough resources to make the fair and principled management of competition for them necessary, but not so few that such management ceases to be justified or feasible. Catastrophic climate change could change all this. Under climate catastrophe, what is required are not principles of justice but rather principles of triage. Most familiar from medical ethics, and battlefield medicine, principles of triage sort people into various categories, and state priority rules for the distribution of resources to people in different categories. In a world beyond the carbon budget, and in which climate catastrophes happen, the language of justice may be entirely misplaced. Principles of triage understood as principles to guide the allocation of extremely scarce survival resources at the macro level, and understood as distinct from principles of justice, are severely under theorised in contemporary moral and political philosophy (McKinnon 2011). In addition to owing future people compensation for harms ripening from risks we impose on them now by barrelling towards depletion of the carbon budget, it may be that we also owe them an intellectual inheritance in the form of an ethics for climate catastrophe. Acknowledgements 19 I am very grateful to Reto Knutti and Joeri Rogelj for their comments on earlier drafts of this paper. Comments made by Dominic Roser and two anonymous referees for the journal also greatly helped to improve the paper. References Adam, D. (2011), ‘Climate Change in Court’, Nature Climate Change 1, May 2011, 127-130. Ackerman, F. (2008), Can We Afford the Future? The Economics of a Warming World. London: Zed Books. Broome, J. (1994), ‘Discounting the Future’, Philosophy and Public Affairs 23(2), 128-56. Broome, J. (2012), Climate Matters. New York: W.W. Norton. Caney, S. (2005), ‘Cosmopolitan Justice, Responsibility and Global Climate Change’, Leiden Journal of International Law 18(4), 747-75. Caney, S. (2012), ‘Just Emissions’, Philosophy and Public Affairs 40(4), 255-300. Coleman, J. (1992), Risks and Wrongs. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Cowen, T. and Parfit, D. (1992), ‘Against the Social Discount Rate’. In: Laslett, P. and Fishkin, J.S. (eds.) Justice Between Age Groups and Generations. New Haven: Yale University Press. Crutzen, P. J., and E. F. Stoermer (2000). ‘The 'Anthropocene'’, Global Change Newsletter 41: 17–18. Duff, R.A. (2009), Answering for Crime: Responsibility and Liability in the Criminal Law. Oxford: Hart. Duff, R.A. (2010), ‘Authority and Responsibility in International Criminal Law’ in S. Besson and J. Tasioulas (eds), The Philosophy of International Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Farber, D.A. (2008), ‘The Case for Climate Compensation: Doing Justice to Climate Change Victims in a Complex World’, Utah Law Review 2, 1-36. Gardiner, S.M. (2011), A Perfect Moral Storm: The Ethical Tragedy of Climate Change, Oxford: Oxford University Press. 20 Hunter, D. and Salzman, J. (2007), ‘Negligence in the Air: The Duty of Care in Climate Change Litigation’. University of Pennsylvania Law Review 155(6), 1741- 94. Hyams, K. and Fawcett. T. (2013), ‘The Ethics of Carbon Offsetting’, Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Climate Change, 4(2), 91-8. Jamieson, D. (2005), ‘Adaptation, Mitigation, and Justice’. In: Sinnott-Armstrong, W. and Howarth, R.B. (eds), Perspectives on Climate Change: Science, Economics, Politics, Ethics. Amsterdam: Elsevier. Jamieson, D. (2014), Reason in a Dark Time: Why the Struggle Against Climate Change Failed, and What It Means for our Future. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Luban, D. (2004), ‘A Theory of Crimes Against Humanity’, Yale Journal of International Law 29, 85-167. McKinnon, C. (2011), Climate Change and Future Justice: Precaution, Compensation and Triage. London: Routledge. Meyer, L. and Roser, D. (2006), ‘Distributive Justice and Climate Change: The Allocation of Emission Rights’, Analyse und Kritik 28, 223-49. Page, E. (2011), ‘Climatic Justice and the Fair Distribution of Atmospheric Burdens: A Conjunctive Account’, The Monist 94(3), 412-32. Rawls, J. (1971). A Theory of Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Rawls, J. (1993), Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press. Rogelj J., McCollum D.L., O'Neill B.C., Riahi K. (2013), ‘2020 emissions levels required to limit warming to below 2°C’. Nature Climate Change 3:405-412. Sen, A. (1992), Inequality Reexamined. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Shue, H. (1980), Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence and U.S. Foreign Policy. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. Shue, H. (1993), ‘Subsistence Emissions and Luxury Emissions’, Law and Policy 15(1), 39-59. Shue, H. (1995), ‘Avoidable Necessity: Global Warming, International Fairness, and Alternative Energy’. In: Shapiro, I. and Wagner DeCew, J. (eds) Theory and Practice: NOMOS XXXVII. New York: NYU Press, 239-64. Shue, H. (2013), ‘Climate Hope: Implementing the Exit Strategy’, Chicago Journal of International Law 13(2), 381-402. 21 Singer, P. (2002), One World: The Ethics of Globalisation. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press). Vanderheiden, S. (2008), Atmospheric Justice: A Political Theory of Climate Change. Oxford: Oxford University Press. work_j2hs42uahnd33jtyizv6p3j5sq ---- Microsoft Word - AARE 2005 Ed Ad & Soc Just.doc BAT05131 Educational Administration and Social Justice Richard Bates Deakin University Vic 3217 Australia rbates@deakin.edu.au Paper submitted to the Annual Conference of the Australian Association for Research in Education, UWS Nov-Dec 2005 Submitted April 2005 2 Abstract This paper argues that social justice is central to the pursuit of education and therefore should also be central to the practice of educational administration. Social justice in education, as elsewhere, demands both distributive justice (which remedies undeserved inequalities) and recognitional justice (which treats cultural differences with understanding and respect). But, given that cultures are always in the process of change, education is a key agency for negotiating cultural change through the exploration and negotiation of difference. Educational administration as a field can no longer escape the consideration of such issues as they are brought to the fore by the recognition of the failure of schools and school systems to ameliorate injustice in the distribution of resources and to recognise and celebrate difference as a means to social and cultural progress. We still need a model of educational administration centered around the problem of the justice and fairness of social and educational arrangements. Given the renewed interest in such issues, perhaps what was impossible twenty five years ago might now be achieved 3 Some two decades ago I called for a model of educational administration centered around ‘…the problem of the justice and fairness of…social and educational arrangements’ (Bates, 1983:39). Mine was a lonely voice, apart from that of Bill Foster (1986) and a small number of similarly marginalised scholars, and the field continued to be dominated by the ‘search for a knowledge base’ rooted in a conceptual separation of educational and administrative issues and the pursuit of a ‘value-free’ science of educational administration (see, for instance the contributors to Boyan, 1988). While voices such as Ken Strike’s (1982) were being raised around the issues of social justice in educational policy; while others such as Young (1971), Bernstein (1975), Bowles & Gintis (1976) and Bourdieu (1977) were transforming the focus of the sociology of education around the complicity of educational practices in reproducing social inequalities; while Dreeben (1968), Jackson (1968), and others were documenting the moral and social order of the classroom and its inequalities; and while others were listening to the voice of radical pedagogy directed in the service of liberation (Apple, 1982; Freire, 1970), educational administration as a field tied itself to the mast of its preferred (positivist) model of science and sailed on, refusing to be distracted by such siren voices. There were, of course, voices at the margins of the field such as those of Thom Greenfield (see Greenfield and Ribbins, 1993) and Chris Hodgkinson (1978, 1991) who were pleading for values to be placed at the heart of the administrative enterprise in education. Greenfield’s attack on the ontological reality of organizations and his insistence that organizations as human creations can be both made and remade through human agency, as well as his attempt to rescue Weber from the heroic stature (mis-) attributed to him as the champion of bureaucracy and reinstate him as the advocate of verstehen and interpretive methodology were truly significant contributions to the field. Or they could have been, had the leading figures in the field understood the significance of what he was saying. But Greenfield, while he clearly had significant concerns with structural issues such as poverty and discrimination, rejected structural analysis and failed to link his subjectivist theory of values with his broader concerns for social justice in any systematic way (see Greenfield and Ribbins, 1993; Bates, 2003a). Hodkinson, of course, develops a convincing case for the place of values in administration (and educational administration in particular). But his position, like that of Greenfield, is subjectivist and essentially relativist. While articulating a formal hierarchy of types of value, Hodgkinson continues to insist that ‘….values do not exist in the world. They are utterly phenomenological, subjective, facts of inner and personal experience, ultimately only susceptible of location within an individual cranium’ (1983:31). Such a position disallows any serious consideration of the social sources of value and the role of the social in the construction of the self (see Taylor, 1989, 1991). Nor does it allow a Weberian analysis of the ways in which values are systematised through organisational and cultural structures (see 4 Samier, 2002). The result, again, is that while values are placed centrally in the study of administration they fail to be linked in any systematic way to issues of social formation or social justice. Indeed, this lacuna is common to most of the discussions of the ethics of educational administration through the decades of the 1980’s and 1990’s. Indeed, such a perspective is still central to the field (Beckner, 2004). Burke’s comment on traditional moral theorizing in public administration is widely applicable to this period of moral theorizing in educational administration which …simply presents, case-like, the range of practical problems and then permits the morally perplexed free reign to pick and choose from a ‘cafeteria of moral principles’ in which competing moral theories end up being treated as equally valid, and since they often yield incompatible solutions they render morality meaningless. (Burke, 1983: 1112 quoted in Samier, 203:75) The result is clearly the ‘conflicts, confusions and contradictions’ that Dempster and his colleagues discovered among principals in their study of ethical decision-making (Dempster et al 2004). However, Dempster et al also fail to make the link between ethical decision making and social justice by suggesting that what principals (and by extension other educational administrators) need is a better ‘general understanding of ethical positions’ (p461). William Greenfield (2004) in his comprehensive discussion of ‘Moral leadership in schools’ provides a broad discussion of various contributions to the placing of values in theories of educational administration. Arguing that ‘…at the very center of the leadership relationship is an essential moral consideration: leading and teaching to what ends and by what means?’ (Greenfield, 2004:174). Noting the growing interest in ‘studying values, ethics and the moral dimensions of educational leadership’ (p174) he carefully describes the various sets of principles advocated as the bases for ethical leadership. In particular he suggests that Schrag’s (1979) four principles foreshadow much of the discussion over the subsequent twenty years. These principles are 1. A moral agent must base his/her decisions on principles that apply to classes of situations, not on a whim of the moment or a predilection for one particular kind of situation… 2. A moral agent should consider the welfare and interests of all who stand to be affected by his/her decision or action… 3. A moral agent has the obligation to base his/her decision on the most complete information relative to the decision that he/she can obtain 4. A conscientious moral agent’s moral judgements are prescriptive [and] answer the question: What ought I to do? (Schrag, 1979: 208-209 quoted in Greenfield 2004:178) Greenfield goes on to show, through his survey of the literature, how these themes are implicit in much of the subsequent debate. Notably, however, 5 Burke’s stricture quoted above is equally applicable to this literature, devoid as it is of substantive content. Bottery (1992) is quoted by Greenfield as a more recent example of similar discourse. His six questions to be asked by school leaders are 1. Does the management of the school promote personal growth? 2. Does it treat people as ends in themselves or as means to ends? 3. Does it foster a rationality which is not only tolerant of criticism, but actually sees it as an essential part of school and society? 4. Does it repudiate the view of human beings as resources to be manipulated, and instead see them as resourceful humans? 5. Does it create an ethos where measures of democracy can be introduced and replicated within the society at large? 6. Does it foster an appreciation of the place of individuals as citizens within their own communities, states and world? (Bottery, 1992 quoted in Greenfield 2004:180) Here, the questions do at least have some content in that they presuppose a commitment to rationality, autonomy, democracy and community. However, even here the links to social justice are not elaborated. Only two of the theorists cited by Greenfield make such a link. Foster (1986) is quoted as advocating a critical humanist position committed to ‘…the idea that the public school administrator has a special duty to improve the institution of schooling so that it is more just and equitable’ (Greenfield, 2004:184). Starratt (1996) is also quoted as advocating an approach to morality that ‘…involves the total person as a human being; it involves the human person living in a community of other moral agents’ (quoted in Greenfield:181). Oddly enough this link between moral behaviour and community is not developed despite the work of, for instance, Strike (1999), Furman (2002) Furman and Starratt (2002), Sergiovanni (1994) or Goodlad (1996). And even where community is invoked as the context of moral leadership, community is defined as ‘the school and its community’, rather than the larger definition of community envisaged by Starratt (2003). However, despite this small progress, the notion of community is set aside in Greenfield’s summary of future directions for the field which are to be focused on: 1. Social relations among school leaders and others 2. Meanings and perspectives underlying school leaders in their relations with others 3. The espoused purposes of school leaders’ actions and orientations towards others 4. The authenticity of school leaders relations with others 5. The emotional dimensions of school leadership 6. The commitments of school leaders (Greenfield, 2004:191) 6 There is nothing here about the links between ethics, community and social justice, but a retreat into the subjective and intersubjective purposes, values and emotions of educational leaders as individuals. This orientation seems to also contextualise the work of the UCEA Center for the Study of Leadership and Ethics which Greenfield so much admires (2004: 174-5). But surely this introspective orientation is a mistake, for, as Furman (2003) makes clear there are significant relationships between ethical leadership, the idea of community, and the notion of social justice. These are particularly well spelt out in Furman and Shields (2003) where it is argued that …there is an essential and dynamic interplay both within and between these concepts that provides a sort of check and balance…democratic processes permit the construction of what social justice means. …social justice, on the other hand, suggests some essential underlying values and offers a construction of moral purpose that provides the compass for common good. (Furman & Shields, 2003:18) It is this idea of the common good that sets out the foundation for approaches to social justice. Or, rather, it is observations of social injustice that set the scene for considerations of social justice and common good. Furman argues, for instance, that Social justice has recently acquired a new intensity and urgency in education for several reasons, including the growing diversity of school populations, … the increasing documentation of the achievement and economic gaps between mainstream and minoritized children,…and the proliferation of analyses of social injustice as played out in schools, including the injustices that may arise from the current policy environment of high-stakes assessment and accountability. (Furman, 2003:5) Similarly, Larson and Murtadha’s (2002) review of the literature on educational leadership and social justice calls for ‘researchers in educational administration who believe that injustice in our schools and communities is neither natural nor inevitable [to] coalesce under an umbrella of inquiry called leadership for social justice’ (2002:135). Such a commitment however, inevitably involves political engagement in a field which, while calling for a commitment to moral values, has always seen administration as a substitute for politics (Bates, 1983). The significance of such commitment is outlined by, for instance, Nieto in her review of public education in the United States where she calls for a renewed commitment to overcoming the injustices faced by minorities in the face of ‘the re-emergence of extraordinarily segregated schools, the almost total dismantling of bilingual education and the continuing vociferous backlash against multicultural education’ (Nieto, 2005: 16). 7 Various such injustices have been explored in the literature on education (though not so widely in the literature on educational administration). Injustices due to poverty (which is often a proxy for various marginalised communities and groups) were, for example, explored by Connell (1994). Arguing that ‘poverty’ is a catch-all concept that disguises radically different situations, Connell show how in industrial countries poverty is a result of maldistribution of resources and wealth, while in the third world poverty is also the result of overall lack of resources and wealth. Moreover, even in wealthy industrialised countries poverty is not static. People move in and out of poverty through the continual restructuring of labour. Again, economic deprivation is shared by people who are quite different in other respects: ethnicity, geography, gender. Yet again, individual poverty may be modified by access to public resources such as education, health services, public libraries etc. This complex of factors makes poverty difficult to address through ‘one size fits all’ programs. This is particularly the case with ‘compensatory education’ designed to make up for the ‘cultural deficit’ of poor communities. Here Connell shows that the presumption that ‘the poor are quite unlike us’ is wrong. For instance, while the rate of poverty in the US in any one year might be between eleven and fifteen percent, over a twenty year period some forty percent of the population may move in and out of poverty (Connell, 1994 quoting Devine and Wright, 1993). ‘We should, then, expect those in poverty at any one time to have a lot in common with the broader working class, including their relations with schools’ (Connell, 1994:131). Such relationships with schools are heavily constrained by power and violence, especially with regard to the urban poor. Educators are well aware of this fact. It is built into their daily lives by history and convention, though we would prefer to ignore this aspect of our lives. Moreover, Connell argues, disdvantage is structurally related to advantage and the redress of inequalities and injustice in education as elsewhere will involve conflict. Disadvantage is always produced through mechanisms that also produce advantage. The institutions that do this are generally defended by their beneficiaries. The beneficiaries of the current educational order are, broadly speaking, the groups with greater economic and institutional power, greater access to the means of persuasion, and the best representation in government and in professions. No one should imagine that educational change in the interests of the poor can be conflict-free. (Connell, 1994:144) And, as we know, conflict over curriculum, pedagogy and assessment is endemic in public discussions of education. But such issues are largely sidestepped in discussions of educational administration. For instance, while Freire’s work on ‘The Pedagogy of the Oppressed’ (1970) has been widely influential in discussions over curriculum and pedagogy, it has been virtually ignored in educational administration. As Larson and Murthada observe while ‘Freire’s treatise on educating oppressed populations has been widely used in 8 curriculum theory…leadership theorists have largely overlooked it. Nevertheless, Freire’s arguments are as relevant to leadership as they are to teaching and learning. (2002:146) In an analysis quite similar to Connell’s and Freire’s, Larson and Murtadha argue that administrative power is used to exclude minority participation. …[M]any well-intentioned leaders maintain institutionalised inequity because they are committed to hierarchical logics that not only fail to question established norms but keep impoverished citizens out of decision making. (Larson & Murtadha, 2002:146) Reasonably enough, such marginalised communities develop a lack of trust in organizations and their leaders. But the result is, ironically, that such mistrust often becomes regarded as a deficiency of the mariginalised and a cause of their marginalisation. Because poor and minority populations have learned to mistrust many public leaders, well-intentioned school leaders often have difficulty in earning their trust and cooperation. Freire explains that the lack of trust poor communities show to those who lead public institutions can be interpreted as an ‘inherent defect’ in poor people, ‘evidence of their intrinsic deficiency’. (Larson & Murtadha, 2002:147) Ironically, such a conclusion can encourage leaders to engage further in those very authoritarian mechanisms of control which alienate the poor in the first place. Contemporary solutions to this dilemma point in two quite different directions: one is in the direction of ‘choice’ and the other the direction of ‘one size fits all’. The issue of choice is very much connected to the idea of school as community where community is seen as a group of similar minded people. Sergiovanni’s (1992) ‘virtuous school’ would seem to be typical of this model. Here the members of the school and its community are held together by shared values and commitments. The heart of the school as a moral community is its covenant of shared values. This covenant provides a basis for determining its morality… The virtuous school subscribes to and uses these moralities as the basis for deciding what its values are and how they will be pursued. (Sergiovanni, 1992:108) But this is a solution that is potentially corrosive and divisive as far as the wider society is concerned. Indeed it is capable of dissolving society in the solvent of Balkanised ‘choice’ for, as Peshkin observes as a result of his case study of such a school 9 The academy epitomizes the case of a community successfully projecting its idiosyncratic outlook onto its school. More than just a community school, however, the academy is a ‘communal’ institution… Communal describes a community whose strong commitment to its own welfare inevitably places it in conflict with other communities that do not accept its doctrinal foundation. A communal school serves an internally integrative or community-maintenance function. That is, it simultaneously links believers together and separates them from non- believers. In its defensive capacity, the academy shields its students and beliefs from competitors by promoting dichotomies not only of we and they, but also of right and wrong. We follow God’s truth in God’s preferred institution; they are the unfortunates of Satan’s dark, unrighteous world. (Peshkin, 1986:282) To be fair, Sergiovanni acknowledges that for large public schools are constituted by pupils from diverse communities ‘There is no easy answer to the difficult question of covenant building’ (1992:109). But in our increasingly diverse societies this is precisely the issue that we face. ‘Choice’ and Balkanisation where ‘virtuous’ schools and their communities glare at each other from behind circled wagons would not seem to be an enticing future. The second response to the problem of diversity is that of ‘one size fits all’ where a ‘community standard’ is set politically by the state as a presumed adjudication of desired values and performance, and where individual communities and schools are held accountable for the achievement of such standards and publicly praised or vilified accordingly. Much educational policy in Western societies is currently driven by such an approach. A typical (if extreme) version is that of the ‘No Child Left Behind Act’ (2002) in the USA. Such moves have some initially attractive features. As Cambron-McCabe & McCarthy (undated) suggest Regardless of one’s position on the school accountability movement, it has focused attention on the widening achievement gap among students and related equity concerns. (p9-10) The intention is to make schools (and especially public schools) more ‘effective’, to remedy the underperformance of under-performing schools, students and communities. While this may be a laudable objective the mechanisms employed may be counter-productive. For instance, the School Effectiveness Movement, which provides some of the justification for the NCLB legislation, is a widespread international phenomenon and a particularly reductionist attempt to lift school performance. Managerially driven, this movement is devoted to raising scores on standardised tests as a mechanism for improving both individual and school performance. ‘School effect’ is isolated as a variable with all environmental 10 variables stripped away statistically. The result is quite the opposite of the complex interaction of historically situated social, cultural, school and community characteristics that Thomson (2003) and Packer (2001) present us with. Community is displaced by economy: a functionalist account of ‘performance’ and the strategic action required to promote performance in a field of uncertainty and competition takes centre stage. But this functionalist account of schooling, as with most functionalist accounts, misrepresents the reality of human interaction in schools and between schools and their communities. It is an account stripped bare of the humanity and complexity of human interaction, one which reduces the person to a simulacrum and sees the relationship between schools and their communities solely in terms of the support or inhibition of ‘performance’ (See Bates, 2004). Indeed, there is growing evidence that, despite the improvements claimed by some schools and school districts, for many groups, processes of exclusion have increased and engagement with learning has decreased, thus producing subsequent declines in performance and exaggerating the differences in performance between advantaged and disadvantaged groups (Cobb & Glass 1999,Fiske & Ladd 2000, Foster 2002, Gilborn and Merza 2000, McNeil, 2000, Strike, 2002, Fuller 2003, Wrigley, 2003, 2004, Black and Wiliam, 2004). The fundamental problem with the ‘one size fits all’ approach is that it decontextualises learning for many students, decoupling it from the worlds in which they live. Not only does the focus on summative assessment linked to high stakes rewards and recriminations inhibit the possibility of richer learning for students, learning contextualised within their history and the possibilities of its reconstruction, it also prevents schools accommodating to the variety of needs brought to the school by its students. The inherent conflict between these two approaches produces significant difficulties for schools and school districts, caught as they are between official demands for standardised performance and policy initiatives directed towards localisation and choice (Fuller, 2003, Hands 2003). As Hands suggests, such decontextualisation destroys any possibility of the creation of community in diverse societies. Along with increasing globalisation over the past several decades, societies have become more pluralistic. Paradoxically, the response to globalisation and the resultant diversity has narrowed many schools’ curricular foci. In Canada and the United States of America, for example, schools have moved toward a unified, single concept of what students should know and value (Shapiro, Sewell & DuCette, 1992: Strike, 2002). Accordingly, a pluralistic approach to education, which recognises and accommodates the needs of a diverse student population, has fallen by the wayside (Shapiro et al, 1992). Within such 11 narrowed educational parameters, administrators are challenged and often unable to accommodate the needs of the various, and increasingly diverse groups of individuals their schools serve. Schools are consequently unable to provide a sense of community (Noddings, 1992; Strike, 2002). (Hands, 2003:123) So how are we to conceive of social justice in such a situation and how can such a conception inform the work of educational administrators? One helpful way is that proposed by Fraser (1997). She suggests that there are two kinds of social justice, one concerned with redistribution and the other with recognition. The issue of redistribution is concerned, pace Rawls (1972), with the issue of redressing undeserved inequalities in wealth, opportunity, access to public services etc. Major concerns here include economic concerns over • Exploitation (having the fruits of one’s labour appropriated for the benefit of others) • Economic marginalisation (being confined to undesirable, poorly paid work or having access to none) • Deprivation (being denied an adequate standard of material living) (Fraser, 1997:13) The general principle of distributive justice is easily understandable in education where gross inequalities in the distribution of such resources are observable and well documented (see for instance Kozol, 1991 for a searing description of such inequalities). One version of distributive justice therefore advocates the equalisation of resources available to all students and schools. The stronger, more Rawlsian, version is to advocate that more than equal resources ought to be allocated to those who suffer from greater disadvantages (be they physical, psychological, cultural, geographic etc). These are easily understood arguments and are publicly rehearsed frequently. I shall not discuss them further. Recognition as a foundation of social justice, is, however, a less well known principle. Here concerns are more cultural than economic, in that cultural justice would involve a positive affirmation of the cultural practices of oppressed groups is required. Fraser suggests that cultural justice involves a principle of recognition that seeks to redress • Cultural domination (being subjected to patterns of interpretation and communication that are associated with another culture and are alien and/or hostile to one’s own) • Non-recognition (being rendered invisible by means of…authoritative representational, communicative, and interpretative practices…) 12 • Disrespect (being routinely maligned or disparaged in stereotypic public cultural representations and/or in everyday life situations) (Fraser, 1997:14) Such principles have profound implications for the construction of curricula, the practice of pedagogies and the methodologies of assessment. And, as curriculum, pedagogy and assessment practices are controlled by processes of educational administration, for educational administration also. In a recent special issue of Educational Administration Quarterly (Marshall, 2004) attempts are made to address such issues within the context of the preparation of educational administrators. The issue ‘….places social justice at the center, so concerns about bureaucracy, hierarchy, efficiency, and even instruction and achievement are secondary’ (p3). Declaring, along with Parker & Shapiro (1992) that ‘there has been very little systematically and formally taught in the areas of race, gender, ethnicity, social class and other areas of difference throughout the entire educational administration curriculum’ (p5), Marshall argues for ‘...a vision of multicultural and multiracial democracy that goes beyond mere tolerance’ (Marshall, 2004:6). Here Marshall begins to address the central problem for twentieth century societies: that of constructing harmony from diversity. As Gray (2000) points out, while a liberal consensus over values might possibly have been reached in traditional societies (though even this is somewhat doubtful) a single system of value is no longer possible. As a consequence of mass migration, new technologies of communication and continued cultural experimentation, nearly all societies today contain several ways of life, with many people belonging to more than one. The liberal ideal of toleration which looks to a rational consensus on the best way of life was born in societies divided on the claims to a single way of life. It cannot show us how to live together in societies that harbour many ways of life. (Gray, 2000:1-2) One solution to this problem, as Touraine (2000) points out, is an authoritarian imposition of particular values through an appeal to an ideal of community and tradition, usually rooted in ethnicity, nationalism or religion. Such authoritarian regimes can have disastrous consequences such as ethnic or religious ‘cleansing’. Even where such authoritarian regimes are imposed by states claiming legitimacy through a ‘democratic’ mandate of ‘fifty per cent plus one’ of the population, and where ‘tolerance’ of other cultures and values is appealed to, the likelihood of marginalisation, exclusion and vilification of minorities is quite high. One alternative to these scenarios is pointed to by Touraine who argues that there is a contemporary temptation to abandon such conflicts of values to ‘the market’. But here the difficulty is that markets are not structures of social action guided by culture and values but rather fields of strategic action which 13 are designed around risk and competitive advantage under conditions of uncertainty. Gray’s solution is the building of institutions within which multiple values can co-exist: the project of modus vivendi. The aim of modus vivendi cannot be to still the conflict of values. It is to reconcile individuals and ways of life honouring conflicting values to a life in common. We do not need common values in order to live together in peace. We need common institutions in which many forms of life can coexist. (Gray, 2000: 5-6) Schools are clearly such institutions. But this does not mean that all ways of life and all kinds of behaviour are acceptable. It means, in reality, that all ways of life are continuously held up to scrutiny and evaluation. Moreover, living alongside each other in such institutional contexts allows also for the process of cultural ‘hybridization’ that Rizvi (1997), among others, points to as a certain consequence of our increasing proximity. Touraine makes a similar point when he observes that ‘…cultures are not, at least in the modern world in which we live, separate and self-contained entities, but modes of managing change as well as systems of order’ (Touraine, 2000,177) As a result of the changing nature of cultures, their internal conflict and reorganisation and their hybridisation, some quite radical alterations in the principles that govern social (and therefore, educational) life are required. Far from appeals to public order, the market, or traditional ways of life, the only possible universalistic ethic upon which social organisation can be based is that of enhanced communication between individuals. Touraine puts it like this: The call for freedom to build a personal life is the only universalist principle that does not impose one form of social organisation and cultural practices. It is not reducible to laissez-faire economics or to pure tolerance, first, because it demands respect for the freedom of all individuals and therefore a rejection of exclusion, and secondly because it demands that any reference to a cultural identity be legitimised in terms of the freedom and equality of all, and not by appeal to a social order, a tradition or the requirements of public order. (Touraine, 2000: 167) The only possible basis for an institutional order that will allow us to live together with our differences is, therefore, a fundamental respect for the autonomy of the individual upon which the economic capabilities argued for by Sen(1992,1999) and the moral capabilities argued for by Nussbaum (2000) can be built. Quite explicitly it is important to assert 14 …that all individuals have a right to freedom and equality, and that there are therefore limits that cannot be transgressed by any government or any code of law. Those limits relate both to cultural rights such as the rights of women and to political rights such as freedom of expression. This position is threatened both by those who would reduce society to the status of a market and by those who want to transform it into a community. (Touraine, 2000: 168) The moral basis of the school as an institution must, then, be a defence of the individual rights of all pupils to freedom and equality, and to cultural, political and economic rights to the development of those capabilities through which they can create their selves and contribute to the wider society (Bates, 2004). This moral basis cannot be established in any school that practices exclusion, nor in any school that fails to provide the basis for communication between individuals pursuing diverse and defensible ways of life. The role of the school then is to protect the individual rights of all pupils and provide for communicative action between the differing ways of life that they value or could come to value, within the context of the school. This implies that the instrumental processes of the school need to be matched with normative processes. These are unlikely to be achieved through current conceptions of the school as a performative agency related principally to the interests of economic organizations. They are more likely to be achieved by schools which build into their practices activities that help form the capacity to reach agreement across boundaries of difference. Nixon and Ranson (1997) argue just this position in response to increasing cultural diversity and the breakdown of cultural certainty within previously confident cultures. In current circumstances, they suggest, the certain consensus of cultures is less obvious than cultural discord. The current sense of cultural fragmentation is widely documented… A prevailing image … is of the compression of cultures. Things formerly held apart are now brought into contact and juxtaposition. Cultures pile on top of one another in heaps without obvious organising principles. There is too much culture to handle and organize into a coherent system of belief systems, means of orientation and practical knowledge. The image of fragmentation presented here is not of culture as something singular and monolithic breaking up into fragments, but of cultures caught in a multiplicity of discordant clashes. (Nixon and Ranson, 1997:208) This image is, for some, an image of despair. Nixon and Ranson however argue quite the opposite for, … as long as there is consensus on issues of value something like effective agreement can be achieved on that basis. But once that consensus has broken down, attempts to build agreement on anything 15 other than a full recognition of difference is doomed to failure. The only hope is to rebuild agreement from the bottom up, so that values can be ‘rediscovered’ through the search for agreement. (Nixon and Ranson 1997:208) The search for agreement through deliberation which acknowledges different values is central to such rediscovery and … the quality of any agreement is dependent not only upon its purposefulness, in respect of the action(s) to which it gives rise, but also upon its inclusiveness, in respect of the deliberative processes that it involves…[D]eliberation is not simply discussion oriented towards action. It is, crucially, a communicative process that actively seeks to engage with values and recognise different value positions…. The point here is not to deny difference, but to ground the recognition of difference in a moral project that holds good across cultural boundaries. (Nixon & Ranson 1997:200-201 itals added) This presents a problem for existing institutions including schools, in that they have an ineluctable tendency towards unification and unitary systems of action and belief. As Douglas (1986) suggests ‘ while the moral project may be one of integration through the recognition of difference, the institutional drive is always towards ‘sameness’ based upon polarisation and exclusion’ (in Nixon and Ranson 1997: 203). Schools are clearly continuously subject to such pressures for conformity through pressures on curriculum, pedagogy and assessment practices. Their moral purpose, in the contemporary world, inheres in their resistance to similarity and exclusion as procedures through which they operate. As Nixon and Ranson suggest The quest for agreement as integrative action is the search for a discourse maintained across the boundaries. It is not an attempt to create a further all-embracing ‘sameness’; but, through imaginative grasp, to hold the differences in tension. It is the urge to argue beyond the point at which differences divide; to love beyond the point at which loyalties define the limits of loyalty; to teach beyond the point at which the normative benchmarks of achievement place a ceiling on student attainment. Ironically, only a culture fragmented by its own multiple compressions and complexities can offer this unique opportunity to learn beyond limits. (Nixon & Ranson 1997:209) Conclusion The conclusion of this argument is that social justice is central to the pursuit of education and therefore should also be central to the practice of educational administration. Moreover, neither administration nor education can be 16 properly practiced through a technical orientation to principles and procedure. At the heart of the educational process is the issue of values. Moreover, the condition of the contemporary world within and between societies exemplifies cultural, social, economic, ethnic, religious, geographic differences as well as those of gender, disability and sexuality. Many of these differences are currently structured, through institutional and political processes, in ways that instantiate advantage and disadvantage. Social justice in education, as elsewhere, demands both distributive justice (which remedies undeserved inequalities) and recognitional justice (which treats cultural differences with understanding and respect). But, given that cultures are always in the process of change, education is a key agency for negotiating cultural change through the exploration and negotiation of difference. Educational administration as a field can no longer escape the consideration of such issues as they are brought to the fore by the recognition of the failure of schools and school systems to ameliorate injustice in the distribution of resources and to recognise and celebrate difference as a means to social and cultural progress. We still need a model of educational administration centered around the problem of the justice and fairness of social and educational arrangements. Given the renewed interest in such issues, perhaps what was impossible twenty five years ago might now be achieved for, as Connell declared back then The education we are speaking of is plainly more than a mere reflection of existing social life; it bears on its reconstitution… Education has fundamental connections with the idea of human emancipation, though it is constantly in danger of being captured for other interests. In a society disfigured by class exploitation, sexual and racial oppression, and in chronic danger of war and environmental destruction, the only education worth the name is one that forms people capable of taking part in their own liberation. (Connell, 1982:207-8) References Apple, M (1982) Education and Power. Boston. Routledge Bates, R (1983) Educational Administration and the Management of Knowledge. Geelong. Australia. Deakin University Press Bates, R (2003a) ‘The Bird that Sets Itself on Fire’ pp 211-235 in R Macmillan (ed) Questioning Leadership: the Greenfield Legacy. London, Ontario. Althouse Press. Bates, R (2003b) Can we live together? The Ethics of Leadership and the Learning Community. Paper presented to the annual conference of the British Educational Leadership, Management and Administration Society. Milton Keynes. October. 17 Bates, R (2004) A Socially Critical View of Public Education. Paper presented to the Annual Conference of the European Conference on Educational Research. Crete. September. Bates, R (2005) Towards a Global Curriculum Arts and Humanities in Higher Education 4(1) 95-109 Beckner, W (2004) Ethics for Educational Leaders. Boston. Allyn & Bacon Begley, P & O Johansson (eds) (2003) The Ethical Dimensions of School Leadership. Dortrecht. Kluwer Academic. Bernstein, B (1975) Class, Codes and Control Vol 3: Towards a Theory of Educational Transmission. London. Routledge. Black, P & D Wiliam (2002) The Formative Purpose. Ch2 in M Wilson (ed) Toward Coherence Between Classroom Assessment and Accountability. Chicago. Chicago University Press. Bourdieu, P & J Passeron (1977) Reproduction in Education, Society and Culture. Sage. London. Bowles, S & Gintis, H (1976) Schooling in Capitalist America. London. Routledge. Boyan, N (ed) (1988) Handbook of Research in Educational Administration. New York. Longman. Cambron-McCabe, N & M McCarthy (undated) Challenges Confronting the Preparation and Development of School Leaders: Implications for Social Justice. wwwleadershipforsocialjustice.org. Downloaded 28.03.05 Cobb, C & G Glass (1999) Ethnic segregation in Arizona Charter Schools. Analysis Archives 7(1) Connell, R., D Ashenden, S Kessler & G Dowsett (1982) Making the Difference: Schools, Families and Social Division Sydney. Allen & Unwin Connell, R (1994) Poverty and Education. Harvard Education Review 64(2) Dempster, N L Carter, M Freakley and L Parry (2004) Conflicts, confusions and contradictions in principals ethical decision-making. Journal of Educational Administration 42(4) 450-461 Dreeben, R (1968) On What is Learned in School. Reading.MA Addison Wesley. Fiskes, E & H Ladd (2000) When Schools Compete: A Cautionary Tale. Washington. Brookings Institute. 18 Foster, S (2002) School Choice and Social Injustice Journal of Philosophy of Education 36(2) 291-308 Foster, W (1986) Paradigms and Promises. Buffalo. NY Prometheus Fraser, N (1977) Justice Interruptus. London. Routledge. Freire, P (1970) Pedagogy of the Oppressed. New York. Continuum. Fuller, B (2003) Education Policy under Cultural Pluralism Education Researcher 32(9) 15-24 Furman, G (ed) (2002) School as Community. Albany NY. New York University Press. Furman, G (2003) Moral Leadership and the Ethic of Community. Values and Ethics in Educational Administration 2(1) 1-7. Furman, G, & C Sheilds (2003) How can educational leaders promote and support social justice and democratic community in schools? Paper presented to the American Educational Research Association. Chicago. April. Furman G & R Starratt (2002) Leadership for democratic community in schools in J Murphy (ed) The Educational Leadership Challenge. Chicago. Chicago University Press. Gewirtz, S (2002) The Mangerial School London. Routledge Gillborn, D and S Mirza (2000) Educational Inequality: Mapping Race, Class and Gender www.ofsted.gov.uk Goodlad, J (1998) Democracy, Education and Community in R Soder (ed) Democracy, Education and Schools. San Francisco. Jossey Bass. Gray, John (2000) The Two Faces of Liberalism. Cambridge. Polity Press. Greenfield T & P Ribbins (1993) Greenfield on Educational Administration. London. Routledge Hands, C (2003) Creating Community Leading & Managing 9(2) 123-128 Hodgkinson, C (1991) Educational Leadership: The Moral Art. Albany NY SUNY Press Hodgkinson, C (1978) Towards a Philosophy of Administration Oxford Basil Blackwell Jackson, P (1968) Life in Classrooms New York. Holt Rinehart Winston Kozol, J (1991) Savage Inequalities. New York. Crown 19 Larson, C & K Murtadha (2002) Leadership fpr Social Justice pp 134-161 in J Murphy (ed) The Educational Leadership Challenge: Redefining Leadership for the 21st Century. Chicago. Chicago University Press Marshall, C (ed) (2004) Educational Administration Quarterly 40(1) McNeill, L (2000) Contradictions of School Reform. New York. Routledge Nieto, S (2005) Public Education in the Twentieth Century and Beyond. Harvard Education Review 75(1) 1-23 Nixon J & Ranson, S (1997) Theorising ‘Agreement’: the moral bases of the emergent professionalism within the new management of education. Discourse 18(2) 197-214 Nussbaum, M (2000) Women and Human Development. New York. Cambridge University Press Packer, M (2001) Changing Classes: School Reform and the New Economy Cambridge. Cambridge University Press Parker, L & J Shapiro (1992) Where is the discussion of diversity in educational administration programs? Journal of School Leadership 2 (7-23) Peshkin, A (1986) God’s Choice Chicago. Chicago University Press Rawls, J (1971) A Theory of Justice Oxford. Clarendon Press Rizvi, F (1997) Beyond the East-West Divide: Education and the Dynamics of Australia-Asia Relations. Australian Educational Researcher 24(1) 13-26. Samier, E (2002) Weber on Education and its Administration Educational Management and Administration 30(1) 27-45 Samier, E (ed) (2003) Ethical Foundations for Educational Administration London Routledge Sen, A (1992) Inequality Re-examined. Cambridge Va. Harvard University Press. Sen, A (1999) Development as Freedom. Oxford. Oxford University Press. Sergiovanni, T (1992) Moral Leadership San Francisco. Jossey-Bass. Sergiovanni, T (1994) Building Community in Schools San Francisco. Jossey- Bass Starratt, R (2003) Centering Educational Administration London. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates 20 Strike, K (1982) Educational Policy and the Just Society Urbana. University of Illinois Press Strike, K (1999) Can Schools be Communities? Educational Administration Quarterly 35(1) 46-70 Taylor, C (1989) Sources of the Self Cambridge MA. Harvard University Press Taylor, C (1991) The Malaise of Modernity Concord, Ontario. Anansi Press Thomson, P (2003) Schooling the Rustbelt Kids. Sydney. Allen & Unwin Touraine, A (2000) Can We Live Together? Stanford. Stanford University Press. Wrigley, T (2003) Is ‘school effectiveness’ anti-democratic? British Journal of Educational Studies 51(2) 89-112 Wrigley, T (2004) ‘School Effectiveness’: the problem of Reductionism British Educational Research Journal 30(2) 227-244 Young, M (ed) (1971) Knowledge and Control London. Collier Macmillan. work_j2us6stctrc6fkp73kjem5i5ta ---- S2398772320000264jra 111..116 SYMPOSIUM ON ART, AESTHETICS, AND INTERNATIONAL JUSTICE MEMORIALIZING DISSENT: JUSTICE PAL IN TOKYO Mark A. Drumbl* Memorials and monuments are envisioned as positive ways to honor victims of atrocity. Such displays are taken as intrinsically benign, respectful, and in accord with the arc of justice. Is this correlation axiomatic, however? Art, after all, may be a vehicle for multiple normativities, contested experiences, and variable veracities. Hence, in order to really speak about the relationships between the aesthetic and international criminal law, one must consider the full range of initiatives—whether pop-up ventures, alleyway graffiti, impromptu ceremonies, street art, and grass- roots public histories—prompted by international criminal trials. Courts may be able to stage their own outreach, to be sure, but they cannot micromanage the outreach of others. And the outreach of others may look and sound strikingly different than that curated and manicured by courts. This essay presents one such othered outreach initiative: a memorial in Tokyo dedicated to Justice Radhabinod Pal of India, who authored a vehement dissent at the International Military Tribunal for the Far East (IMTFE). The IMTFE was established in 1946 to prosecute Japan’s leadership in the aftermath of the Second World War. Pal would have acquitted each defendant. This essay describes Justice Pal’s legal philosophy, situates his place in the currents of international law, and reflects on the broader role of memorials as discursive sites. Justice Pal’s Arc of Life Pal’s journey is remarkable in that he hailed from a poor rural family yet became a distinguished lecturer at India’s premier institution of postgraduate education.1 Pal was born on January 27, 1886, in the small village of Salimpur (Kushtia District, Bengal) in British-occupied India. Today, this village is part of Bangladesh. Pal was initially educated in local schools and later studied mathematics and law at Presidency College Calcutta (now Kolkata) and the Law College of the University of Calcutta. Pal was appointed to the IMTFE after it had begun its work to address a striking imbalance in the number of Asian judges. In November 1948, the IMTFE sentenced seven convicts to death, sixteen to life imprisonment, and two to fixed prison terms (twenty years and seven years). Pal alone would have acquitted each defendant. Pal led a rich life in international law following his iconic dissent. From 1952 until 1966, he was a member of the UN International Law Commission (ILC). He became Chair in 1958. Pal died on January 10, 1967, at the age of 80. He had fourteen children. * Class of 1975 Alumni Professor of Law and Director, Transnational Law Institute, Washington and Lee University. I thank Marina Aksenova, Karima Bennoune, Maggie Gardner, and Shannon Fyfe for helpful input on earlier versions of this text. 1 Milinda Banerjee, Does International Criminal Justice Require a Sovereign? Historicising Radhabinod Pal’s Tokyo Judgment in Light of His “Indian” Legal Philosophy, 21 FICHL PUBLICATION SERIES 67, 72, 76 (2014). doi:10.1017/aju.2020.26 © Mark A. Drumbl 2020. This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited. 111 https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/f52001/pdf/ https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/f52001/pdf/ http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ B.S. Chimni, writing in the American Journal of International Law in 2018, worried that “the non-availability of the state practice of third world countries, and also the paucity of scholarly writings on the subject, allows the iden- tification of rules of [customary international law] primarily on the basis of state practice of advanced capitalist nations and the opinions of their scholars.”2 Pal was an early spark behind the au courant conversation about whether international law truly is international.3 His work product contributed to postcolonial legal theory and unmasked the embeddedness of racism within the international legal order. Pal also evidences Anthea Roberts’s observation that, when it comes to approaching international law, “each of us brings our biography into play.”4 Pal’s Dissent In contrast to the International Military Tribunal at Nuremberg, several of the eleven IMTFE judges submitted separate concurring and dissenting opinions. Sir William Webb, the Australian judge who presided over the trial, posited that in sentencing the convicts the IMTFE should have taken into account that the Japanese Emperor had not been indicted. The French judge lamented procedural shortcomings. The Dutch judge, somewhat like Pal, concluded that no conspiracy existed and accordingly would have found five of the defendants innocent. The Canadian judge signed onto the majority but in private communications with his government criticized the IMTFE.5 Delfin Jaranilla, the Filipino judge who had personally survived the Bataan death march of 1942, wanted to punish more harshly. Together with the Chinese judge (who joined the majority), Judge Jaranilla shared some of Pal’s concerns with imperialism and colonialism, but saw Japan’s participation in aggressive war and other crimes as utterly condemnable. He—along with the rest of the majority—emphasized the atrocities perpetrated by Japanese armed forces in territories previously subject to Western colonization. Pal’s separate opinion was the only totally dissenting one. Pal “did not in the least affirm all of Japan’s past actions; he simply held that the defendants’ actions were not illegal in an indictable sense.”6 In contradistinction to American prosecutor Joseph Keenan’s vision of the virtuous Allies and the repugnant Axis powers, Pal grav- itated towards a construction of the Pacific War as a “tragic contest” in which all sides “shared alike a common grammar of militaristic imperial aggression.”7 Pal believed the IMTFE’s mandate—which covered the years 1928 to 1945—was too narrow and too convenient.8 Pal was disturbed by an international tribunal that he took as pun- ishing Japanese aggression in territories that had previously been seized through imperial violence, for example, by the United Kingdom in Burma and India, the Netherlands in Indonesia, and the United States in the Philippines.9 Assuredly, Pal’s approach risks seeming to justify impunity for Japanese abuses in the name of anti-colonialism, thereby effectively revictimizing people for the fact of being colonized.10 2 B.S. Chimni, Customary International Law: A Third World Perspective, 112 AJIL 1, 6 (2018). 3 ANTHEA ROBERTS, IS INTERNATIONAL LAW INTERNATIONAL? (2017). 4 Anthea Roberts, Is International Law International? Continuing the Conversation, EJIL:TALK! (Feb. 9, 2018). 5 Timothy Brook, The Tokyo Judgment and the Rape of Nanking, 60 J. ASIAN STUD. 673, 690 (2001). 6 Ushimura Kei, Pal’s “Dissentient Judgment” Reconsidered: Some Notes on Postwar Japan’s Responses to the Opinion, 19 JAPAN REV. 215, 215 (2007). 7 Banerjee, supra note 1, at 89. 8 Brook, supra note 5, at 694. 9 Robert Cryer, The Tokyo International Military Tribunal and Crimes Against Peace (Aggression): Is There Anything to Learn?, in SEEKING ACCOUNTABILITY FOR THE UNLAWFUL USE OF FORCE 80, 82 (Leila Nadya Sadat ed., 2018). 10 Immi Tallgren, Watching Tokyo Trial, 5 LONDON REV. INT’L L. 291, 304 (2017) (noting that Pal’s dissent “appears insensitive to the suffering of victims”). 112 AJIL UNBOUND Vol. 114 https://www.cambridge.org/core/journals/american-journal-of-international-law/article/customary-international-law-a-third-world-perspective/DEDB6DB43A3B5A613B68FDBE56E20A20 https://www.oxfordscholarship.com/view/10.1093/oso/9780190696412.001.0001/oso-9780190696412 https://www.ejiltalk.org/is-international-law-international-continuing-the-conversation/ https://www.jstor.org/stable/2700106 https://www.jstor.org/stable/25791314?seq=1 https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/f52001/pdf/ https://www.jstor.org/stable/2700106 https://www.cambridge.org/core/books/seeking-accountability-for-the-unlawful-use-of-force/tokyo-international-military-tribunal-and-crimes-against-peace-aggression-is-there-anything-to-learn/823DB45086EFFBAD8E0073D04134B8EA https://academic.oup.com/lril/article-abstract/5/2/291/4621435?redirectedFrom=fulltext Pal emphasized that charges of conspiracy and crimes against peace were precarious because of retroactivity and legality. One major thread in Pal’s dissent is that the time had not come for Japan to be judged criminally respon- sible under international law for its actions during the war. The law had not ripened and, accordingly, prosecution was a hasty, opportunistic, even ulterior act. The colonized states, newly independent, were temporal laggards and hence entered a world where the crystallization of law would happen without their participation—they became subjected to this putatively universal law. Since, from Pal’s view, “no category of war became a crime in interna- tional law up to the date of the commencement of the world war under our consideration,” to prosecute such crimes was “a sham employment of legal process for the satisfaction of a thirst for revenge.”11 Pal insisted that international law could only legitimately punish if it organically emerged through and from a genuinely equal consensus of all states. For Pal, an international tribunal cannot deliver justice outside of an under- lying egalitarian order among states. Pal worried that an international court or tribunal would simply transfer the power of certain states to another level. Query as to what Pal would say today, about the International Criminal Court, for example, in light of his view that the international community has not as yet developed into “the world commonwealth” and perhaps as yet no particular group of nations can claim to be the custodian of “the common good”. International life is not yet organized into a community under the rule of law.12 In the case of conventional war crimes, Pal found that jurisdiction existed but also determined that there was no factual nexus with the accused. Pal investigated these charges “and eventually concluded that the evidence pre- sented to the Tribunal was not sufficient to establish the criminal responsibility of the defendants.”13 Pal ques- tioned whether the Japanese leadership could be implicated in this violence through doctrines of command responsibility. This nexus—that of the commander to the criminal conduct—continues to vex international crim- inal law today.14 As Timothy Brook explicates, Pal “[c]ombines a conservative legal positivism that refuses to innovate beyond existing law with a radicalism that regards the politics within which a court operates relevant to the adequacy of its findings.”15 This tension arises throughout Pal’s dissent. For example, the one-sided nature of the charges rattled him in that he felt it betrayed law’s need to be evenhanded. The omission of the atomic bombs at Hiroshima and Nagasaki, in particular, galled him.16 Pal mordantly noted that any claims that the breaches of shared humanity should be crim- inally punished “were non-existent” when another state decided to deploy atomic weaponry. On a different note, Pal was even less charitable than the IMTFE majority when it came to the sexual torture and enforced prostitution of many thousands of women. Pal’s dissent has been lamented for its callousness regarding gender-based violence.17 He was a skeptic, wincingly so; he was curtly dismissive and did not wish for law to enter 11 Int’l Military Tribunal for the Far East Judgement, dissentient opinion of Judge Pal, paras. 37 & 152 [hereinafter Pal Dissent]. 12 Id. at para 104. 13 Nakajima Takeshi, The Tokyo Tribunal, Justice Pal and the Revisionist Distortion of History, 9 ASIA-PAC. J. Article ID 3627, at 3 (Issue 44, Number 3) (2011). 14 See, e,g., the 2018 acquittal in the Bemba case delivered by a fractured Appeals Chamber of the International Criminal Court. Prosecutor v. Jean-Pierre Bemba Gombo, Case No. ICC-01/05-01/08A, Judgement on Appeal (June 8, 2018). 15 Brook, supra note 5, at 694 (citing the work of Elizabeth Kopelman). See also generally Elizabeth Kopelman, Ideology and International Law: The Dissent of the Indian Justice at the Tokyo War Crimes Tribunal, 23 N.Y.U. J. INT’L L. & POL. 373 (1990–91). 16 Brook, supra note 5 at 692. 17 Banerjee, supra note 1, at 96 (“Pal did (in hindsight, irresponsibly, and perhaps unforgivably) express doubts about the extent of Japanese war crimes; thus he suggested that reports of the Rape of Nanking (Nanjing) might have been exaggerated.”). 2020 MEMORIALIZING DISSENT: JUSTICE PAL IN TOKYO 113 http://www.sdh-fact.com/CL02_1/65_S4.pdf http://www.sdh-fact.com/CL02_1/65_S4.pdf http://apjjf.org/2011/9/44/Nakajima-Takeshi/3627/article.html https://www.icc-cpi.int/CourtRecords/CR2018_02984.PDF https://www.icc-cpi.int/CourtRecords/CR2018_02984.PDF https://www.jstor.org/stable/2700106 https://heinonline.org/HOL/LandingPage?handle=hein.journals/nyuilp23&div=19&id=&page= https://heinonline.org/HOL/LandingPage?handle=hein.journals/nyuilp23&div=19&id=&page= https://www.jstor.org/stable/2700106 https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/f52001/pdf/ that space. In his own words, pulled from his dissent: “I might mention in this connection that even the published accounts of Nanking ‘rape’ could not be accepted by the world without some suspicion of exaggeration.”18 Pal’s sardonic air-quotes around the word rape, intentionally introduced, speak volumes. Pal After Tokyo While on the ILC, Pal abstained from voting on the Draft Code of Offences against the Peace and Security of Mankind that had been proposed in 1954 and debated at the Sixth Session of the ILC in Paris. He thereby advanced his philosophical vision as articulated at the IMTFE, arguing that “given the nature of international rela- tions at that period, a mere code of international criminal law could not bring about real justice. It might indeed have the opposite effect of giving to dominant powers, victorious in wars, an excuse to commit injustices.”19 Pal wished to build “an international community under the reign of law. . . in which nationality or race should find no place.”20 He argued for the development of an international agency (which he called the “Super State”) that “he believed would eradicate wars and overcome racial discrimination.”21 He advocated Gandhism and pacifism, and “was a believer in humanism based on the philosophy of ‘dharma’ from ancient India.”22 Pal’s dissent, then, and his subsequent writings connect broadly to ongoing conversations about the legacies of imperialism, evenhandedness in adjudication, the new international economic order, judicial independence, inter- generational equity, the role of dissent in the life of international criminal trials, and the place of history in discourse about law. Pal’s legal and political philosophy was complex and fluid. Accordingly, as Kirsten Sellars notes, “during the Cold War decades Pal found common ground with Japanese nationalists over pan-Asianism and anti-commu- nism, with the non-aligned movement over anti-colonialism and self-determination, and with Western anti-mili- tarists over American foreign policies—and was lionized by them all.”23 Pal has garnered somewhat of a cult of personality, in particular, among Japanese nationalists. At times, Pal’s views expressed in his IMTFE dissent have been mischaracterized by Japanese nationalists; yet Pal himself colluded in this distortion in his postwar visits to Japan by appealing to this audience and by expressing empathy for convicted Japanese officials and soldiers.24 Tokyo’s Pal Memorial Pal assuredly remains a contested figure in Japan, notably among constituencies that advocate for greater redress and justice for Japanese war-time atrocities. The two memorials erected in his honor in Japan situate themselves within these political currents. One memorial is in Tokyo (completed in 2005), the other in Kyoto (completed in 1997). Very few international judges have ever been lauded in brick, imagery, and mortar. Pal’s honorific memorials, therefore, are quite distinctive. As the international community increasingly welcomes commemorations and monuments as ele- ments of reparative and transitional justice, uncomfortable sites such as the Pal memorials merit greater discussion.25 18 Pal Dissent, supra note 11, at para. 1064. 19 Banerjee, supra note 1, at 109. 20 Takeshi, supra note 13, at 6 (citing Pal). 21 Id. 22 Id. at 7. 23 Kirsten Sellars, Imperfect Justice at Nuremberg and Tokyo, 21 EJIL 1085, 1100 (2011). 24 Id. at 1099–1100 (discussing Yuma Totani’s work). 25 For example, both the Special Rapporteur on the promotion of truth, justice, reparation and guarantees of non-recurrence and the Special Rapporteur in the field of cultural rights have emphasized the roles of art and memorialization. 114 AJIL UNBOUND Vol. 114 http://www.sdh-fact.com/CL02_1/65_S4.pdf https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/f52001/pdf/ http://apjjf.org/2011/9/44/Nakajima-Takeshi/3627/article.html http://apjjf.org/2011/9/44/Nakajima-Takeshi/3627/article.html http://apjjf.org/2011/9/44/Nakajima-Takeshi/3627/article.html https://academic.oup.com/ejil/article/21/4/1085/418156 https://academic.oup.com/ejil/article/21/4/1085/418156 https://www.ohchr.org/EN/Issues/TruthJusticeReparation/Pages/Index.aspx https://www.ohchr.org/EN/NewsEvents/Pages/DisplayNews.aspx?NewsID=22908&LangID=E Pal’s Tokyo memorial26 sits between the Yasukuni Shrine, dedicated to war dead, and Yushukan, a controversial museum—chided for its historical revisionism and nationalism—that commits itself to the Japanese military. This memorial reclines in a courtyard of statuary. On its immediate left (when one faces it) is a statue commemorating a Japanese mother, widowed, who clutches three children (“Statue of War Widow with Children”), which was erected in 1975. On the right of Pal is a monument commemorating a patrol boat and sailors; to the further right of that is an old bronze cannon. More or less across from Pal, though slightly diagonal, are three statues in a row that commemorate animals for their service in war: a dog, a horse, and a carrier pigeon. I have elsewhere discussed what first struck me when visiting the Pal Memorial, namely, its invocation of the Confederate States of America. Jefferson Davis’s words, delivered in 1888 after the South’s defeat in the U.S. Civil War, are engraved on a plaque on the front of the site; Pal himself mentions Davis’s words in the last line of his approximately 250,000 word IMTFE dissent.27 I have also elaborated elsewhere on Pal’s footprints beyond the FIG. 1: Memorial to Judge Pal. Photograph taken by the author on July 2, 2018. 26 See Fig. 1. 27 Mark Drumbl, Judge Pal with Jefferson Davis in Tokyo, OPINIO JURIS (Mar. 23, 2019). The quote reads: “When Time shall have softened passion and prejudice, when Reason shall have stripped the mask from misrepresentation, then Justice, holding evenly her scales, will require much of past censure and praise to change places.” 2020 MEMORIALIZING DISSENT: JUSTICE PAL IN TOKYO 115 https://opiniojuris.org/2019/03/23/judge-pal-with-jefferson-davis-in-tokyo/ memorial today: his spectral presence in how Tokyo variably remembers World War II through six museums.28 I now hope to ask and speculate about a different question: in light of what we know of Pal’s legal philosophy, what might he think about the memorial edified in his honor? Would he be flattered? Would he cringe? Would he think he deserved it? My intuition is that one answer might lie in Pal’s own vision of discursive justice. For Pal, the attainment of global equality would arise through dissensus, tension, and dialogue among transcendental ideals and ground-level strug- gles.29 The memorials certainly create such spaces—physically, conversationally, and emotionally. Another surmised answer might lie in Pal’s vision of the role of the judge. Latha Varadarajan notes that “[t]he extent and virulence of Pal’s disagreement was unexpected . . . . Even the newly independent Indian state distanced itself from the dissent by declaring that Pal had been chosen as ‘an eminent judge in his individual capacity,’ and that he was not ‘India’s representative’ on the tribunal.”30 Pal underscored judicial independence. He lived it. General MacArthur put considerable pressure upon the IMTFE to deliver a unanimous guilty verdict. Pal resisted.31 He eschewed the idea that there had to be a singular narrative among judges. Hence, it seems plausible that he would find the memorialization of what others have called his “radical dissent” as consistent with, rather than inimical or antithetical to, a genuine overarching project of international criminal justice.32 Conclusion In sum, Pal’s Tokyo memorial inspires as it rankles. It consoles, confronts, and confounds. It is an example of how art, from below, responds to international criminal trials implemented from above. Memorialization of law, assumed to be congenial, cordial, and victim-centric, may not be so simple. Justice Pal’s memorial forms part of the aesthetics of public histories—the representations on (and from) the “street”—of courtroom accountability. Art may interface unpredictably with the self-promotional goals of international justice. Art may not always fit with the outreach efforts of international courts, nor may it merely flit by those efforts. Instead (and indeed), it might vex those efforts—discomfit them—and convect countercurrents. 28 Mark Drumbl, Scattered Thoughts on Art as Contrarian: Justice Pal’s Memorial in Tokyo, ART & INT’L JUST. INITIATIVE (June 26, 2019). 29 Banerjee, supra note 1, at 111. 30 Latha Varadarajan, The Trials of Imperialism: Radhabinod Pal’s Dissent at the Tokyo Tribunal, EUR. J. INT’L REL. 1, 6 (2014). 31 Id. at 6. 32 Neha Jain, Radical Dissents in International Criminal Trials, 28 EJIL 1163 (2017); Hemi Mistry, The Paradox of Dissent: Judicial Dissent and the Projects of International Criminal Justice, 13 J. INT’L CRIM. JUST. 449 (2015). 116 AJIL UNBOUND Vol. 114 https://artij.org/en/blog.html https://www.legal-tools.org/doc/f52001/pdf/ https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/abs/10.1177/1354066114555775?journalCode=ejta https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/abs/10.1177/1354066114555775?journalCode=ejta https://academic.oup.com/ejil/article/28/4/1163/4866314 https://academic.oup.com/jicj/article-abstract/13/3/449/890724 https://academic.oup.com/jicj/article-abstract/13/3/449/890724 Memorializing Dissent: Justice Pal in Tokyo Justice Pal's Arc of Life Pal's Dissent Pal After Tokyo Tokyo's Pal Memorial Conclusion work_j4oxvq34qjdefltulwcfsew2pe ---- 4 Pacific Geographies #51 • January/February 2019 To illustrate governance arbitrage in action, I use the example of the justice system in Solomon Islands, for two reasons. The first is that delivering justice is the definitional task of effective governance that asserts legitimate authority (Finnemore, 1996), which is in turn the first goal of development under the good governance agenda (World Bank, 1997). The second is that justice in Solomon Islands has long been an area of hybrid contestation between the governances codes of the Western liberal state, customary practices and Christian churches against a backdrop of unfettered capitalism. I build on the discussion of the justice system to contrast elites and non-elites as governance arbitrageurs of differing resources, experience and skill at operating in the hybrid ‘mix of formal and informal institutions through which the exercise of power plays out’ (Allen et al., 2017:p.7). Elaborating on the connection between governance, legitimacy, authority and justice, Allen and others (2007) are right that power ‘plays out’ through institutions. Institutions legitimate power when they provide some kind of public good, creating an obligation by the public to support that institution. This legitimate power expresses itself as authority, as opposed to illegitimate, coercive and larcenous power (Barnett & Finnemore, 1999). Turning to governance, Solomon Islands does not have a single, unified justice system with discrete venues designed as an authoritative and legitimate institution, except on paper. Instead, the hybrid reality of justice-seeking in Solomon Islands means that courts are sites for mixing governance codes in ways that are dynamic and uncertain. In contrast to the cut-and-dried ways of common law legalism, the hybrid actions of Islander governance arbitrageurs make sense in the context of an ‘arbitrary governance environment’ characterised by the ‘constant making and unmaking of public authority... Bigmen justice: Governance arbitrage in Solomon Islands justice delivery Rob Lamontagne1 The Solomon Islands state remains weak despite decades of development assistance. While there are many possible causes to explain this weakness, one important yet relatively neglected expla- nation is that development efforts have failed to account for the country’s hybrid governance in which governance codes of Western liberalism, capitalism, Christianity and Melanesian custom interact. Although hybridity in the region is explored by academic observers (Boege et al., 2008; Mac Ginty & Richmond, 2016; Wallis et al., 2016; Forsyth et al., 2017), there is a need for con- tributions that help explain the practical impacts of hybrid governance. In other words, under- standing that governance in Solomon Islands is hybrid is the first step; understanding how hybrid governance functions is the second. To help fill that gap, this paper introduces a new concept, ‘governance arbitrage’, to explain how actors, elite and non-elite alike, navigate a hybrid governance environment by calling on diffe- rent governance codes in the pursuit of their goals. I argue the concept of arbitrage – profiting by taking advantage of the difference in values for the same commodity – is useful for interpreting the actions of Islanders because it shows how hybridity works in practice. 1 Griffith University, School of Government and International Relations, N72 170 Kessels Rd, Nathan QLD 4111, Australia, ORCID 0000-0001-5871-205X. DOI: 10.23791/510411 Abstract: Solomon Islands remains underdeveloped despite decades of development assistance. I argue this is due, in part, to the failure to account for the country’s hybrid governance in which governance codes of Western libera- lism, capitalism, Christianity and Melanesian custom interact. There is a need for contributions that discuss and ex- plain the practical impacts of hybrid governance on those who live in the region. To help fill that gap, I review and analyse the relevant secondary literature, introducing a new concept, ‘governance arbitrage’, to explain how actors navigate a hybrid governance environment. I show governance arbitrage is widespread within the justice system, and is a tool used by elites and non-elites alike. I conclude by suggesting possible new avenues for research Keywords: Melanesia; governance; governance arbitrage; hybridity [Submitted as Research Note: 25 January 2019, Acceptance of the revised manuscript: 20 February 2019] 5Pacific Geographies #51 • January/February 2019 where it is frequently unclear to the citizenry which authority, if any, will take responsibility for handling any given complaint’ (Tapscott, 2016:p.42). In this paper, I review the relevant secondary literature and make an argument for governance arbitrage as having explanatory advantages over an alternative such as forum shopping. This review of literature in the region brings together voices on both the Solomon Islands justice space as well as anthropological perspectives on how people – both elites and non-elites – have operated in other parts of Melanesia to identify and explain a phenomenon that holds back development efforts in Solomon Islands. This raises a concern about conflating literatures by using literature that is specific to Solomon Islands as well as another literature that includes Melanesia more broadly, particularly Solomon Islands’ neighbours of Papua New Guinea and Vanuatu. There are a number of reasons why I have chosen to override this concern and go forward. First among them is that Melanesia as a region of social science study is defined by the omnipresent diversity between governance codes. As a result, bringing perspectives from one part of Melanesia to another can illuminate common issues. At the same time, adopting national boundaries as barriers to research seems inappropriate. Finally, I am following in the tradition of the literature by comparing like-cases to generate fruitful insights (Douglas, 2005; Evans et al., 2010). My argument is as follows: in a developing state like Solomon Islands, development requires effective governance. Effective governance, in turn, requires a justice system that resolve disputes in a way that is seen to be fair and reasonable by participants; in a word, the justice system must be legitimate. That legitimacy comes from rightful authority, but in Solomon Islands, what precisely constitutes rightful authority is a highly complex problem and contested issue. This paper begins with a brief description of the social geography of Solomon Islands through the four codes of governance at work in the country, and use that discussion to define elites and non-elites in Islander history. I elaborate on hybridity, and then defend governance arbitrage as a better heuristic tool than the alternative of forum shopping. Having developed my theoretical approach, I then use the example of the Solomon Islands justice system as a space where governance arbitrage is omnipresent. I close by summarising and offering my views of what governance arbitrage’s use in future research programs. My objective is to show that governance arbitrage is a novel and useful description for an ongoing phenomenon with deep roots in Solomon Islands in particular and Melanesia more broadly. My conclusion is that understanding governance arbitrage is vital for explaining the pervasive uncertainty for justice-seekers in the region. Solomon Islands: a social geography of four governance codes Solomon Islands is an archipelagic developing country in the southwest Pacific. A part of Melanesia, it is part of the most ethnolinguistically diverse region on the planet, with the varieties of governance to match (Putt et al., 2018). The substrate of Islander governance is the traditional, or customary code. It includes a vast range of variations, but common features to be discussed shortly it together as a code (Wittgenstein, 2009). While the customary preceded contact with Westerners, custom since sustained contact is called kastom in Melanesian pidgin, reflecting its hybrid reality. Alongside custom is Christianity, introduced two centuries ago and the faith of virtually all Islanders today. Alongside both is the Weberian liberal state, with its institutions and assumptions of selfhood, citizenship and governance. Alongside all three is capitalism, the pursuit of economic profit by private actors. This section explains what these codes are, in the small space available. The basic building block of Solomon Islands society is the customary code of governance; and the basic building Figure 1: Child playing with an old tyre at a beach on Savo Island, Solomon Islands. S o u rc e: A n n e Pa u ls e n . 6 Pacific Geographies #51 • January/February 2019 block of the customary is what is now called the wantok. A group of people who view themselves as sharing a common identity reified by mutual reciprocity (de Renzio, 1999), wantoks express ‘cooperation, caring and reciprocal support, and a shared attachment to locality’ (Nanau, 2018:p.244). Literally meaning ‘one talk’ in pidgin, wantoks often share a common language, but may also offer commonality across, but not exclusive to, kinship ties, geographical origins, social associations, and religious affiliations. Wantoks remain ‘the primary reference point for most Solomon Islanders’ (Allen et al., 2017:p.6), and wantokism is the omnipresent ‘invisible hand’ (Nanau, 2018:p.248) of social interaction and governance in the country. Like kastom, the wantok is a social phenomenon that emerged in response to contact with other, foreign governance codes, but by the same token, represented something that had existed long before contact. Fundamentally a ‘system of generalised obligations and supports’, wantoks express a customary approach to constantly shifting interrelations between groups, that sees exclusivity as alien (Brigg, 2009:pp.151-152). As Harrison argues, the kastom code with its focus on ‘transactional networks and lines of transmission rather than ... discrete and bounded entities’ (2006:pp.70-71) leaves individuals as ‘partible’ people who act ‘as composite beings constituted of the detached parts/relationships of other persons through prior ... exchange’ (Mosko, 2010:p.215). Kastom and wantokism model a sense of selfhood based on dividual selves: selves defined in relations to others; meaning generated by what Harrison calls the ‘commerce of cultures’ (1993). Intertwined after nearly two centuries of missionary activity and holding the allegiance of 95% of the Solomon Islands population, Christian practice is also based in sociality and collectivity. Literally parochial in a way that has hybridised well with kastom, Islanders themselves regard the two codes as ‘inextricably linked’ (Timmer, 2008:p.199) even if they disagree about the precisely how and to what extent, and see the two codes as focusing on reciprocity, spirituality and a rich cultural ritual practice (Douglas, 2005). However, tensions abide, and at least one observer notes how a Protestant- dominated Melanesian Christianity based on an unmediated relationship with God can drive individualism in a way that undermines social stability (Robbins, 2004). Yet Whiteman argues that far from being passive recipients of a foreign creed, Islander Christians were, and are, ‘active participants, reinterpreting, modifying, accepting and rejecting change advocated by the missionary’ (1983:p.432). Two other Western governance codes, liberalism and capitalism, resolve the tension between individualism and collectivity by relying on a vision of the ‘possessive individual’ who is the unique ‘the proprietor of his own person and capacities, for which he owes nothing to society’ (Macpherson, 1962:p.263). The individual citizen is the basic component of Western liberalism expressed through a Weberian state structure with an elected political leadership and an implementing disinterested bureaucracy together exercising rational-legal authority (Weber, 2013). Of course, being a ‘possessive individual’ is not merely a statement of political citizenship, but a description of an egoistic, rational, benefit-maximising economic actor who is committed to the formal equality of all citizens under the law, but also to the pursuit of inequality in private profit under capitalism. Although the capitalist and the liberal codes of governance intertwine, they do so in tension (Sykes, 2007). The uneven interaction between these four entangled governance codes has resulted in what Porter and others call ‘social disintegration’. This is particularly clear in the example of youth and migration. In a post-colonial country with half the population under 25, and the young stuck between the past while also struggling to build a stable future, there is a growing sense that the traditional institutions are inappropriate or obsolete. This feeling is strongest in the towns and city (2015:p.2), places where the governance and social and economic ‘mix is changing fast[est]’ (Moore, 2014:p.29). Returning to wantoks, we can see this disintegration and reformation occurring in real time. Wantoks may provide social cohesion, comfort and support in the village, but transformed by an aggressive brand of capitalism and weak liberal government systems, wantoks of elite actors reshape reciprocity from a means of sharing and mutuality into a means of ‘exploitation and political expediency’ (Nanau, 2018:p.248). This ‘manipulation of custom’ (Fraenkel, 2004) is not confined to elites, but elites by definition have the power, authority and capacity to act more freely than non-elites, as Fraenkel points out in his discussion of militia leaders strategically misapplying customary principles of compensatory justice to rationalise their attempt to blackmail the liberal state for money payments to call a truce. This example from the violent ethnic Tensions of 1998-2003 is only one example of how the customary has become "increasingly monetised, separated from its social foundations, and often used instrumentally to extort and intimidate, or otherwise used to promote particular material or political interests" (Allen et al., 2017:p.5). Grassroots and bigmen: elites and non-elites The question of defining and outlining elites and non-elites is a question of the hybrid interaction of governance codes in every way as much as kastom or the wantok. This section discusses who elites are in Solomon Islanders, as well as non-elites. There are three kinds of elites: those pre- contact, during the colonial era, and finally the current, post-colonial era. In contrast, the relative ratio of non- elites is surprisingly consistent across all three eras, with change coming very recently. In Islander societies, the vast majority of people live by subsistence farming from time immemorial. Even today, between 80% and 90% of the population still live in this way, in village life. These non-elites – what Martin calls the grassroots (2007) – have recently begun taking part in the capitalist economy, whether in small doses in the village, or by moving to provincial towns or the capital, Honiara. By virtue of exerting capitalist agency, grassroots individuals join the ‘working class’, the Melanesian term for those engaged in the wage economy. If successful, they also begin ascending toward elite status. On the other hand, elite status is 7Pacific Geographies #51 • January/February 2019 something that must be both earned by the individual, and conferred on the individual by others. The sources of legitimating elite authority before sustained contact with Westerners lie in the ability of individuals to set themselves above by ritual achievement (earning the post-contact status of ‘great man’) or by entrepreneurial, acquisitive achievement (the ‘bigman’) (Harrison, 1993:p.156; compare Sahlins, 1963). Later, Western capitalists and colonialists attempted to define elites by offering more alien monikers: bigmen and great men were ‘chiefs’, and elite chiefs were ‘paramount chiefs’ (Goddard, 2010:p.11). As we will see shortly, British colonial officials attempted to create a new, specifically collaborationist elite by appointing some chiefs as ‘headmen’. Finally, in the post-colonial era, the rapid hybridisation of governance created a proudly, aggressively Western kind of elite figure eager to define themselves through their liberal and capitalist identities as a ‘possessive individual’: the ‘big shots’ who had risen to the top end of the working class (Martin, 2007). Hybridity Rather than crossing a fluid boundary between public and private, I argue that in Solomon Islands, people repurpose codes of governance, whether custom, Christian, capitalist or liberal, with elites having much more practice, facility and therefore ability at doing so. However, to say actors switch between discrete codes is to present them with solid and stable, not fluid and dynamic, boundaries. Moreover, while some codes have closer relationships than others (for example custom and Christianity as kastom), they are all interrelated. Capitalism has found its way into even the most remote corners of the country, while liberalism has outpaced the reach of its feeble Western state – providing at least ideas to Islanders, if not basic services. This section shows that hybridity is the most useful heuristic, as some of the preeminent experts in its use have said, to ‘explor[e] complex processes of interaction and transformation occurring between different institutional and social forms, and normative systems’ (Forsyth et al., 2017:p.408) in Solomon Islands. We must understand how the four governance codes in Solomon Islands interact and constitute a hybrid governance space. Why is this specifically hybrid, and not something else? To say these codes have been and are hybridising is mixture, but it is not random bricolage. At the same time, making this an example of Marxist or Hegelian dialectic is too a priori prescriptive. ‘Norm-grafting’ implies a simplistic addition of one plus one making two. Hybridity, however, is just right: it captures the fluid dynamism of different codes interacting, but on unequal terms according to context. The rest of this subsection unpacks hybridity before introducing examples of authority arbitrage that illustrate how elite actors call on different codes of governance to assert authority against a backdrop of rapid social, economic, political and cultural change. Hybridity is a relatively new entrant into scholarly research. Emerging from postmodernism as a repurposing of the Marxist dialectic, hybridity became a key concern of postcolonial writers and then with observers of globalisation after the Cold War. Hybridity has since become a common reference among the new and fast- growing literature of peacebuilding, if only slowly rising to prominence in others. Its rapid rise stems from the problems encountered in stopping and preventing civil conflicts, (counter-) insurgencies and mass atrocities in the developing world. As Boege and others point out (2008), the good governance agenda relied on the presence of legitimate institutions; these institutions required an authoritative state; authoritative states required liberalism to be legitimate, and so it was necessary to build or impose liberal states on developing countries. However, from Africa to Afghanistan and Iraq to Solomon Islands, it rapidly became clear that the Western liberal state "does not have a privileged position as the political framework that provides security, welfare and representation; it has to share authority, legitimacy and Figure 2: Peter rows the ferryboat between Taro and Supizae in Choiseul. Every year the distance gets longer because both islands are shrinking as the sea level rises. Hundreds of times a week, Peter rows his passengers across the short stretch of water taking people to work and returning them home. Because of climate change, the township of Taro will relocate to the mainland leaving Peter facing an uncertain future. S o u rc e: P a tr ic k R o se . 8 Pacific Geographies #51 • January/February 2019 capacity with other [community and customary] structures. In short, we are confronted with hybrid political codes, and they differ considerably from the [W]estern model state" (Boege et al., 2008:p.10). Hybridity therefore emerged from the need to describe something that ‘good governance’ could not: the reality that effective governance is not found in the liberal state alone, but nestled among other ‘local’, religious, customary, formal and informal sources. While this description is relatively uncontroversial, what is controversial is the attempt of some to operationalise hybridity and make the descriptive, prescriptive. Naturally, this prescriptive hybridity is a ‘double-edged sword’ (Wallis et al., 2016:p.161). Drawing on evidence from hybrid peacebuilding efforts in Papua New Guinea, Solomon Islands and Timor-Leste, Wallis, Kent and Jeffery point out that this ‘instrumental’ (ibid.) hybridity can fail as a result of Western technical experts attempting to appropriate local customs for their own ends, or equating so-called local ownership with locals being responsible for implementing the strategies Western experts give them (Boege et al., 2008). Yet, while prescriptive hybridity has its ‘dark side’ (Wallis et al., 2016:p.159), hybridity simply is, and observers and practitioners must use it as a descriptive tool to better understand how governance functions. Actors must accommodate some form of instrumental hybridity to have any effect at all, and that is what governance arbitrageurs are an example of. How hybrid is forum shopping? To clarify the benefit of using governance arbitrage in a specifically hybrid environment, let us contrast it with another candidate used in an excellent article on the phenomenon of (North) Solomon Islands justice- seeking: ‘forum shopping’ (Cooper, 2018)[footnote: I thank an anonymous reviewer for making this point.]. Forum shopping, a term taken from Anglo- American legal studies, is the ‘act of seeking the most advantageous venue in which to try a [legal] case’ (Algero 1999:p.79). It assumes, however that both vertical and horizontal fora options (whether appealing to higher courts or moving cases from one jurisdiction to another) are distinct, discrete, and legible to the participants. Forum shopping means weighing and up selecting mutually-exclusive fora, i.e. going from one forum to another forum and choosing between them, as one would between different items at the market. Forum shopping requires a choice between a liberal resolution process, a Christian resolution process or a customary resolution process. While these labels can be attached to different examples, the hard-and-fast distinction breaks down on contact with reality: each is captured in turn by the others on shifting ground. The analytic clarity that forum shopping offers should not be dismissed, but in Solomon Islands justice-seeking, the choice is not between fora, because the national justice space is essentially one big forum, in which the four governance codes vie and overlap. If forum shopping is about choosing different options within one framework of governance, governance arbitrage is about both choosing and creating different options for governance outcomes amongst intertwined governance codes. In contrast to forum shopping, where justice-seeking strategies are delimited by space and time (i.e. changing venue or pursuing an appeal by scheduled dates with final judgements handed down), hybrid justice-seeking means arbitrageurs seek their outcomes without regard to time (no sub-ideal outcome is ever final) and ranging across different hybrid spaces: examples include local courts that meld Western liberalism and customary-Christian kastom, pursuing Christian church dispute resolution if unsuccessful, or petitioning the state for compensation which is non-customary by calling on kastom (Evans et al., 2010). Distinct, discrete and legible accurately describe forum shopping, but do not accurately describe this process. We must move beyond a ‘hierarchical approach to legal pluralism’ in Melanesia that ‘obscure[s] a more complex interplay between the interwoven spheres of “traditional law” and “state law” and a new sphere of “blended’ law”’ (Corrin, 2009:p.29). Governance arbitrage and justice This section uses justice as the example of how governance arbitrage works in practice. I begin with outlining the Islander justice system, pre-contact, before moving onto the installation of a Western justice system under the British Solomon Islands Protectorate and colonial attempts to use governance arbitrage to assert their authority. I then outline the decline and collapse of the justice system outside the capital – the Native Courts, then area, or local courts – since independence. Throughout, we see elites and grassroots alike pursuing justice, but the elites using their greater resources as arbitrageurs to tip the procedures and outcomes of the justice system in their favour. Before Westerners, dispute resolution in Melanesia included a variety of methods from sorcery to vendetta-warfare, but not courts as Westerners would think of them. Customary practices did not constitute a formal, written code of laws because there was no writing and therefore no formality. Different groups with their unique requirements of right and wrong, fairness and justice made the reconciliation of differing accounts difficult without a common body of law or venues. Even the collaboration of relevant chiefs virtually never resulted in a final, acceptable settlement, a feature of Island justice that survives in this century. Understandable due to the fluid boundaries of different groups’ cultural practices, compensation in the form of gifts, people, and other offerings such as cultural rituals often represented the only way to bring conflict to a close. It was only with the coming of Christian missionaries – themselves often brutal in the treatment of sinners – that peaceful mediation became a method of conflict resolution (Harrison, 1993; Goddard, 2010). The coming of colonial power in the late nineteenth century filled a role of the disinterested, bureaucratic adjudicator whose rulings were seen as unbiased and therefore legitimate. In the British Solomon Islands Protectorate, officials followed the Australian example in neighbouring Papua and New Guinea by sending junior officers on patrol (Dinnen & Braithwaite, 2009), in part to serve as circuit judges. However, because these District Officers were so few in number – at its height, the Protectorate employed 100 staff to oversee 28,000 9Pacific Geographies #51 • January/February 2019 square kilometres (McIntyre, 2014) – the British co-opted customary institutions by appointing bigmen as ‘headmen’ (Putt et al., 2018) of their village or district and presidents of the ‘native court’, to be assisted by other Islanders serving as constable and clerk (Evans et al., 2010). Banned from issuing decisions on religious matters, the headmen were both empowered as the link between customary and Western justice, yet disempowered as their authority came from Western justice alone (Goddard, 2010): whether officers, or the later magistrates, and finally European judges in the capital, colonial officials always reserved final adjudicating power for themselves. British officials built on their cooptation strategy and formalised the headman system as the Native Courts (later renamed ‘area courts’ under the Local Government Act) dealing with land disputes and customary matters. After the Second World War, headmen were slowly replaced by administrative resident clerks, support magistrates on their circuits, and issue processes. As the decolonisation push began in the mid-1960s, locally-elected councils were created to oversee the courts. However, while the councils were meant to oversee the courts and administer their areas, they were created with no rules for how they were supposed to operate. Plans were drawn up to devolve real powers to the councils, but that was never done (Timmer, 2008). Nevertheless, there was a functional justice system upon independence in 1978. Sixty-five local courts sat around the country, heard cases and issued decisions to settle disputes or to refer them to the liberal system. The courts worked well as part of a hybrid order: wantoks were represented through the councils, and the distant coercive powers of the state supported and strengthened the courts. Most important was that the courts operated in a way that was legible to Islanders with jurisdiction over problems they wanted solved: ‘a range of social order problems’ (Porter et al., 2015:p.7) like public drunkenness and delinquency and also the single most important problem in Solomon Islands political economy, land rights. However, this also represented a binary problem that hybridity could not solve: the impossibility of codifying customary land rights in liberal law, starting with the reality that is customary land use, the use of the land itself could never be legitimately alienated to the liberal system, only stolen (a matter in any event beyond the remit of the courts, which were banned from adjudicating whether or not land was customary or not). Outside observers have often noted the virtually inevitable failure of ‘chiefs’, however defined, to settle land disputes in Solomon Islands, and the resulting failure of the local courts to solve these disputes (Evans et al., 2010; Goddard, 2010); however, the impossibility of reconciling two completely different governance codes to a legitimate state in either goes largely unremarked. Independence was followed by the withdrawal of the state from the local courts, and from the rural areas more broadly. Funding dropped for the resident clerks who served as the linchpins of the integrated justice system. The waiting times for oversight and action by the Western system lengthened, undermining the courts’ legitimacy and attractiveness by progressively removing avenues for appeal referral. The courts evaporated, and by 1986, halved in number. As what was left of the system was nationalised and placed entirely within the liberal state judiciary, justice became inaccessible (Hammergren & Isser, 2015:p.10). By 1998, only three courts remained outside the capital, and magistrates could no longer effectively go on circuits to hear cases (Porter et al., 2015). This vanishing from the periphery ‘severely hampered [locals’] ability to deal with social crises’ (Porter et al., 2015:p.2); in 1998 the Tensions broke out and the local courts and their councils were finally abolished in law; no court would hear a case until 2010 (Hammergren & Isser, 2015). Communities filled the gap as best they could with ‘local arrangements’, but these arrangements lacked the legitimacy of the courts. They were overburdened with the sheer range of complaints they had to resolve, whether public order issues, those dealing with land rights or logging or murder (Porter et al., 2015:p.2). While it is true that Islanders ‘navigate [hybrid] power relations in more subtle and nuanced ways’ than are readily apparent to outside observers (Allen et al., 2017: 9), the absence of the courts’ provision of a space to transparently categorise and refer disputes, combined with the radical social, political, economic and cultural changes occurring, opened opportunities of exploitation for unscrupulous elites. The ‘retreat of the state’ (Dinnen & Allen, 2016:p.79) strengthened elite authority by removing alternate sources of effective governance (Evans et al., 2010). Without the courts, justice provision naturally fell back to bigmen and elders, which reinforced ‘immense practical challenges in determining who the chiefs [were]’ (Timmer, 2008:p.197). Weakened communities ‘routinely challenged’ claims of authority by bigmen, especially those who had sinned according to church doctrine by ‘partak[ing] in alcohol and...are seen as colluding with loggers’ (Porter et al., 2015,p.7). Collusion with loggers brings up the acetylene-torch role of capitalism in undermining justice and effective governance in Solomon Islands (Allen, 2011), and the role of logging in Solomon Islands’s political economy cannot be understated. Currently the country’s main export commodity earning 70 per cent of all export income (DFAT, 2014), the logging industry has played a major role in destroying both local ecologies and traditional modes of governance by incentivising the breakdown in traditional collective ownership administered by chiefs and elders, and its replacement by local ‘trustees’ according to Western law who behave as private owners and take the profits, permitting fees and bribes for themselves (Baines, 2015; Monson, 2015), creating an atmosphere of universal suspicion. This brings us to the core of governance arbitrage. Those who wield authority do so by appeals to multiple sources of legitimacy, often at once. The kastom bigman is a Western state trustee of a wantok’s traditional land while serving as a Member of Parliament and a Christian church elder – and if they are not actually the same person, they usually share kin or personal networks (Baines, 2015). Once a bigman would proffer justice with oversight by 10 Pacific Geographies #51 • January/February 2019 elders; then church pastors offering their religious views entered the picture; then Western authorities with their liberal state functions; and finally capitalists with their eagerness to pay pennies to make millions. Now, elites range across these codes to gain and maintain authority, even when asserting authority under one code undermines authority in another; in fact, the practice undermines each code but leaves the power concentrated in relatively few hands (Cooper, 2018; McDougall, 2015; Monson, 2015). Bigmen can and often do abuse their customary authority to line their own pockets with rents and payments from logging companies, the state and foreign aid actors rather than distributing these funds to their kin, and escape retribution by calling on precisely the traditional roles of authority they abuse (Baines, 2015; Hviding, 2015). Likewise, the withdrawal of that very system under the postcolonial state is another example of the new elite asserting its authority by deprioritising the provision of effective and non- personalised justice outside provincial capitals. While Solomon Islands is a state cursed with the wicked problems of building a liberal democratic state without much money in a context of economic and ethnic volatility, the agency of national elites should not be denied, especially when considering the elites’ decades-long approach to subverting the Constitutional mandate to decentralise power and fighting federalism and power-sharing (Nanau, 2017a; Nanau, 2017b; Scales, 2008). Fundamentally, while much remains outside the control of elites, much does. At the grassroots, non-elite Islanders also understand the differences between governance codes, but see them as generally complementary. Customary, chiefly procedures, Christian mediation and local liberal courts can be complementary (McDougall & Kere, 2012). More importantly, ‘local communities ... [combine] the most efficacious elements of indigenous and introduced regulatory systems with reasonable efficiency’ (Evans et al., 2010:p.29) in classic arbitrageur fashion. While these views may be optimistic by privileging inputs of governance arbitrage while discounting the outputs of widespread governance failure in terms of ecological disaster, ongoing ethnic tensions, and state weakness that strengthens elites, the fact remains that elites and non-elites alike are attempting to make the best of a less-than-ideal situation through governance arbitrage in a hybrid governance environment. Conclusion This paper has argued that one vital yet neglected explanation for the poor development outcomes in Solomon Islands is the failure to account for the hybrid interaction of governance codes – customary, Christian, capitalist and liberal – in the country. As a result, despite the presence of four governance codes, effective hybrid governance remains harder to find. Nevertheless, Islander elites and non-elites alike make the best of the situation through governance arbitrage. In this paper, we have seen litigants bringing customary expectations to a liberal court; bringing the liberal to customary practices; bringing the Christian to both. In hybridity, we see not just distinct venues, but fluidity and overlap between governance codes – and while national elites may be able to navigate the system through the acquisition of experience and the deployment of resources, non-elites in local communities struggle to make do; the difference between the two groups is one’s luxury of strategy, the others’ reliance on tactics. Both groups, however, are trying to make the best of their situation, to get what they want. The purpose of this paper has been to identify a gap in the literature, namely examples of hybridity in Melanesia in action. The purpose has been to argue for the concept of governance arbitrage as a useful addition to the literature, using the example of the Solomon Islands justice space. The goal is to recommend new pathways for research, e.g. moving away from the assumption that the liberal justice system with its ‘possessive individuals’ is the only way to justice and finding examples of governance arbitrage in the emergent legal system. More important that this is seeing Solomon Islands’s politics as politics, and looking for governance arbitrage both in the actions of its political actors and as a core component of the slow building of a political settlement in the country. Reference List Algero, M. (1999) In Defense of Forum Shopping: A Realistic Look at Selecting a Venue. Nebraska Law Review, 78 (1), 79-112. Allen, M. (2011) The Political Economy of Logging in Solomon Islands. In: Duncan, R. (Ed.) The Political Economy of Economic Reform in the Pacific. Mandaluyong City, Asian Development Bank, 277-302. Allen, M., Dinnen, S., Keen, M. & Allen, B. (2017) New Pathways Across Old Terrain? SSGM Discussion Paper 2017/5. Canberra, SSGM. Baines, G. (2015) Solomon Islands is Unprepared to Manage a Minerals-Based Economy. SSGM Discussion Paper 2015/6. Canberra, SSGM. Barnett, M., & Finnemore, M. (1999) The Politics, Power, and Pathologies of International Organizations. International Organization, 53 (4), 699-732. Boege, V., Brown, A., Clements, K. & Nolan, A. (2008) On Hybrid Political Orders and Emerging States: State Formation in the Context of 'Fragility'. Berlin, Berghof Research Center for Constructive Conflict Management. Brigg, M. (2009) Wantokism and state building in Solomon Islands: A response to Fukuyama. Pacific Economic Bulletin, 24 (3), 148-161. Cooper, J. (2018) State Capacity and Gender Inequality: Experimental evidence from Papua New Guinea. Available from: http://jasper-cooper.com/ papers/Cooper_CAP.pdf. Corrin, J. (2009) Moving Beyond the Hierarchical Approach to Legal Pluralism in the South Pacific. The Journal of Legal Pluralism and Unofficial Law, 41 (59), 29-48. de Renzio, P. (1999) Bigmen and Wantoks: Social Capital and Group Behaviour in Papua New Guinea. WIDER Project Meeting, Group Behaviour and Development. Helsinki: United Nations University. Dinnen, S. & Allen, M. (2016) State Absence and State Formation in Solomon Islands: Reflections on Agency, Scale and Hybridity. Development and Change. 47 (1), 76-97. Dinnen, S. & Braithwaite, J. (2009) Reinventing policing through the prism of the colonial kiap. Policing and Society, 19 (2), 161-173. Douglas, B. (2005) Christian Custom and the Church as Structure in 'Weak States' in Melanesia. Paper given at \ Civil Society, Religion & Global Governance: Paradigms of Power & Persuasion Conference, 1-2 September 2005, Canberra, Australia. Evans, D., M. Goddard and D. Paterson. (2011) A Comparative Analysis of Village Courts of Papua New Guinea, Island Courts of Vanuatu and Local Courts of Solomon Islands. Washington, DC: World Bank. Finnemore, M. (1996) Norms, Culture, and World Politics: Insights from Sociology's Institutionalism. International Organization, 50, 325-47. Forsyth, M., L. Kent, S. Dinnen, J. Wallis and S. Bose (2017) Hybridity in peacebuilding and development: a critical approach. Third World Thematics: A TWQ Journal, 2 (4), 407-421. Fraenkel, J. (2004) The Manipulation of Custom: From uprising to intervention in the Solomon Islands. Wellington, Victoria University Press. Goddard, M. 2010. Justice Delivered Locally: Solomon Islands: Literature Review. Washington, 11Pacific Geographies #51 • January/February 2019 Rob Lamontagne [rob.lamontagne@griffithuni.edu.au] is a PhD researcher with Griffith University and Visiting Fellow at the Development Policy Centre in Canberra, Australia, where he studies anticorruption strategies in the region. His research is supported by a Griffith University Research Training Program International Scholarship. DC: The World Bank. Hammergren, L. & Isser, D. (2015) Institutional and Fiscal Analysis of Local-Level Courts in Solomon Islands. Washington, DC: World Bank. Harrison, S. (1993) The Commerce of Cultures in Melanesia. Man, 28 (1), new series, 139-158. Harrison, S. (2006) Fracturing resemblances: Identity and mimetic conflict in Melanesia and the West. New York & Oxford: Berghahn Books. Hviding, E. (2015) Big Money in the Rural: Wealth and Dispossession in Western Solomons Political Economy. The Journal of Pacific History, 50 (4), 473-485. Mac Ginty, R. & Richmond, O. (2016) The fallacy of constructing hybrid political orders: A reappraisal of the hybrid turn in peacebuilding. International Peacekeeping 23 (2), 1-21. Macpherson, C. (1962) The political theory of possessive individualism: Hobbes to Locke. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Martin, K. (2007) Your Own Buai You Must Buy: The Ideology of Possessive Individualism in Papua New Guinea. Anthropological Forum, 17 (3), 285-298, McDougall, D. (2015) Customary Authority and State Withdrawal in Solomon Islands: Resilience or Tenacity?. The Journal of Pacific History, 50 (4), 450-472. McDougall, D. & Kere, J. (2012) Christianity, Custom, and Law: Conflict and Peacemaking in the Post-Conflict Solomon Islands. In: Brigg, M. & Bleiker, R. (Eds.) Mediating Across Difference: Indigenous, Oceanic, and Asian Approaches to Conflict Resolution. Honolulu, University of Hawaii Press, 141-162. McIntyre, W. (2014) Winding up the British Empire in the Pacific Islands. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Monson, R. (2015) From Taovia to Trustee: Urbanisation, Land Disputes and Social Differentiation in Kakabona, The Journal of Pacific History. 50 (4), 437-449. Moore, C. (2014) Moving forward by asking the right questions of the past. In: Wood, T. & Howes, S. (Eds) Debating Ten Years of RAMSI: Reflections on the Regional Assistance Mission to Solomon Islands, 27-30. Canberra: Development Policy Centre. Mosko, M. (2010) Partible penitents: Dividual personhood and Christian practice in Melanesia and the West. The Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute, 16 (2), 215-240. Nanau, G. (2018) Wantoks and kastom (Solomon Islands, Melanesia). In: Ledeneva, A. (ed.) The Global Encyclopaedia of Informality: Understanding Social and Cultural Complexity, Volume 1. London, University College London Press, 244-247. Porter, D., Isser, D. & Venning, P. (2015) Toward More Effective and Legitimate Institutions to Handle Problems of Justice in Solomon Islands. Washington, The World Bank. Putt, J., Dinnen, S., Keen, M. & Batley, J. (2018) The RAMSI Legacy for Policing in the Pacific Region. Canberra, Department of Pacific Affairs. Robbins, J. (2004). Becoming Sinners: Christianity and Moral Torment in a Papua New Guinea Society. Oakland: University of California Press. Sahlins, M. (1963) Poor Man, Rich Man, Big-Man, Chief: Political Types in Melanesia. Comparative Studies in Society and History. 5 (3), 285-303. Sykes, K. (2007) Interrogating Individuals: The Theory of Possessive Individualism in the Western Pacific. Anthropological Forum, 17 (3), 213-224. Tapscott, R. (2016) Local Security and the (Un) making of Public Authority in Gulu, Northern Uganda. African Affairs, 116/462, 39-59. Timmer, J. (2008) Kastom and Theocracy: A Reflection on Governance from the Uttermost Part Of The World. In: Dinnen, S. & Firth, S. (Eds.) Politics and State Building in Solomon Islands, 194-212. Canberra: ANU E-Press. Wallis, J., Jeffery, R. & Kent, L. (2016) Political reconciliation in Timor Leste, Solomon Islands and Bougainville: the dark side of hybridity. Australian Journal of International Affairs. 70 (2), 159-178. World Bank. (1997) World Development Report 1997: The State in a Changing World. New York: Oxford University Press. Weber, M. 2013. Economy and Society. (Eds.) Roth, G. & Wittich, C. Oakland: University of California Press. Whiteman, D. (1983) Melanesians and Missionaries. Pasadena: William Carey Library. Figure 3: Typical housing on the Solomon Islands, Savo Island. S o u rc e: A n n e Pa u ls e n . work_j4oyjsabefhlzhye6ieyjinmrm ---- Suicide and community justice Suicide and community justice PHILLIPS, Jake , PADFIELD, Nicola and GELSTHORPE, Loraine Available from Sheffield Hallam University Research Archive (SHURA) at: http://shura.shu.ac.uk/22311/ This document is the author deposited version. You are advised to consult the publisher's version if you wish to cite from it. Published version PHILLIPS, Jake, PADFIELD, Nicola and GELSTHORPE, Loraine (2018). Suicide and community justice. Health and Justice, 6. Copyright and re-use policy See http://shura.shu.ac.uk/information.html Sheffield Hallam University Research Archive http://shura.shu.ac.uk http://shura.shu.ac.uk/ http://shura.shu.ac.uk/information.html RESEARCH ARTICLE Open Access Suicide and community justice Jake Phillips1* , Nicola Padfield2 and Loraine Gelsthorpe3 Abstract Background: There has long been concern about the number of people who die in custody in England and Wales, particularly in prisons or police stations. The concern is obviously heightened when people die either at their own hand, or at the hands of others. Yet there has been selective critical gaze, and people who die whilst under probation or community supervision have been neglected (Phillips, J, Gelsthorpe, L, Padfield, N., Criminology & Criminal Justice, https://doi.org/10.1177/1748895817745939, 2017). Given that there is evidence to suggest that contact with the criminal justice system in non-custodial settings is associated with higher mortality rates than those found in the general population, such neglect is concerning. Methods: This article explores data which has been published since 2016 by Her Majesty’s Prison and Probation Service (HMPPS) on the deaths of offenders whilst under supervision. We draw on data which is collected by probation providers and collated by HMPPS to present original analyses, with particular focus on deaths by suicide. We calculate rates of self-inflicted deaths and rate ratios with the general population and the prison population. Results: The suicide rates for all groups within the sample are higher than the general population. Conclusions: We explore the utility of the data in helping us to understand the trends regarding people dying whilst under probation supervision with a particular focus on suicide, and highlight areas where the dataset is deficient. We conclude that whilst the dataset can be used to calculate headline rates of suicide it raises many questions in terms of the extant risks that people on probation face, and we explore ways in which the data can be used more fully to understand this important social and public health issue. We consider ways in which the dataset could be matched with other datasets in future research so that health issues might be brought into the analysis, and reflect on other research methodologies which would add depth to our understanding of why the mortality rate amongst people in contact with the criminal justice system is higher than in the general population. Background This paper explores the under-researched topic of deaths (particularly self-inflicted deaths) of those subject to criminal justice supervision in the community. Whilst in England and Wales there has been significant public (and academic) concern for deaths in custody, the deaths of those subject to community supervision has not been studied nearly as much. This became a cause of concern to us in 2010, when the Howard League for Penal Reform encouraged us to analyse information that they had received from individual Probation Trusts (as they were then): see Gelsthorpe et al. 2012. Since then, more official data has been published. We show in this paper that despite limitations with these official data, there are some important concerns when it comes to suicides of people under probation supervision. What do we already know about suicide in community justice settings? Although the deaths of offenders under supervision have received less attention than deaths in other criminal just- ice institutions, there is evidence to suggest that the mortality rate amongst this group is higher than the gen- eral population. The following section provides a review of existing research on this topic focusing on prevalence, official statistics and risk factors. Prevalence Pritchard et al. (1997) examined suicide and violent death in a six-year cohort of male probationers in England and Wales for the period 1990–1995 and found that males (aged 17–54) had twice the death rate and * Correspondence: jake.phillips@shu.ac.uk 1Department of Law and Criminology, Sheffield Hallam University, Heart of the Campus, Collegiate Crescent, Sheffield S10 2BQ, England Full list of author information is available at the end of the article Health and Justice © The Author(s). 2018 Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons license, and indicate if changes were made. Phillips et al. Health and Justice (2018) 6:14 https://doi.org/10.1186/s40352-018-0072-7 http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1186/s40352-018-0072-7&domain=pdf http://orcid.org/0000-0002-7606-6423 https://doi.org/10.1177/1748895817745939 mailto:jake.phillips@shu.ac.uk http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ nine times the suicide rate of the general population. In a study for the Home Office, Sattar (2001) found that deaths following release from prison tended to occur soon after release. A quarter of deaths within her sample of 1267 deaths in the community in England and Wales occurred within 4 weeks of release from prison. Over half occurred within 12 weeks of release, and within 24 weeks of release just under three-quarters of all deaths had occurred. The number of deaths in the community was five times the rate of the 236 deaths of prisoners and the mortality rate for supervisees was four times higher than that for the male general population rate. Solomon and Silvestri (2008) found that the rate of suicide of those under probation supervision was nine times higher than in the general population and higher than in prison. King et al. (2015) found that 13% of suicides in the general population in England and Wales were, or had recently been, under supervision by the criminal justice system. They reported a significantly elevated suicide risk among individuals who had received a police caution, recently been released from prison, recently completed a super- vised community sentence, served other community dis- posals, been remanded as a suspect on police bail and/or dealt with by no further action (King et al., 2015: 175). Interestingly, they found that ‘individuals serving a com- munity sentence under the supervision of the Probation Service had a relatively low risk’ of suicide (2015: 175). King et al.’s (2015: 176) findings were not statistically sig- nificant but they point to the potential for probation supervision to serve as a protective factor and ‘as a crucial source of support for vulnerable offenders’. Internationally, a high mortality rate amongst people under criminal justice supervision in the community has been consistently identified. For example, In Australia, Biles et al. (1999) found that people under probation supervision had a higher mortality rate and suicide rate than the general population and people in prison. In Denmark Webb et al.’s (2011) analysis of suicide amongst people in the criminal justice system identified an elevated risk of suicide and Binswanger et al.’s (2011) analysis of deaths after leaving prison shows a mortality rate that is 3.5 times that of the general population. Trends and themes within English and welsh official data In 2016 the Ministry of Justice (2016a) published, for the first time, data on deaths of offenders in the community. This means that we now have a better understanding of trends regarding deaths within the offender population in England and Wales. That said, it should be noted there are concerns about the quality of these data, as noted elsewhere (Phillips et al. 2017). For example, data from the years 2010–2013 contained many gaps in terms of type of sentence and offence category and it is worth noting that recording practices changed over this period. Moreover, two (out of 21) Community Rehabilitation Companies1 (CRCs) failed to report any information by the Government’s cut-off date for the 2016–17 figures (Ministry of Justice 2017a). In order to compensate for this latter point, Government statisticians have adjusted figures for earlier years by removing deaths from the two missing CRCs ‘so as to provide like-for-like compar- isons with 2016-17’ (Ministry of Justice 2017a: 5). Thus trends over time should be treated with care. Nevertheless, the government’s own publication shows that in 2015/2016, there were 725 deaths of offenders in the community, a 30% increase from 557 deaths in the previous year. Of the 725 deaths, 264 were self-inflicted and show an increase of 40% from 2014/2015. A further 68 were accidental and there were 22 apparent homi- cides. The remaining 371 were from natural causes or unknown (Ministry of Justice, 2017a) Table 1. The category ‘unclassified’ refers to those deaths for which a cause was unknown at the time of reporting and has not yet been updated. The latest data give some in- formation on deaths of offenders supervised by the National Probation Service as opposed to those super- vised by the CRC and there are some points worth not- ing here. As the Ministry of Justice highlights; In 2016/17, the proportion of self-inflicted deaths in the NPS was lower than the proportion of deaths due to natural causes. The opposite is true of the CRCs, where self-inflicted deaths accounted for a higher proportion of deaths than natural causes. This is only partly explained by the different age distributions of the supervised offenders. When comparing on a like- for- like basis, CRCs had a drop in the number of self-inflicted deaths compared to the previous year, whereas the NPS saw an increase (Ministry of Justice, 2017a: 8). Drawing again upon the Ministry of Justice’s analysis, there were 372 deaths of offenders under post-release supervision in the community after a custodial sentence in 2016/17. This represented 50% of all deaths of of- fenders in the community. Although in absolute terms these were similar between NPS and CRCs (180 and 192 deaths respectively), in relative terms deaths under post- release supervision represented 41% of all deaths in the community while supervised by CRCs, but 65% of all deaths while supervised by the NPS. The Ministry of Justice argues that the ‘sizeable increase in deaths since 2014/15, corresponds with the introduction of ORA2’. However, it is worth noting that when we break this down to people on post-release supervision, the number of self-inflicted deaths rose from 40 to 117 (an increase of almost 300% between 2013/14 and 2016/17) whilst the number of people on post-release supervision rose Phillips et al. Health and Justice (2018) 6:14 Page 2 of 12 by just 179% (from 39,565 to 70,650) over the same period (Ministry of Justice, 2016b). It is possible that changes to recording methods account for some of this discrepancy but probably not all. It is also worth commenting on deaths that occur within Approved Premises (AP) which are used to house high risk offenders, normally upon release from prison. APs are akin to bail hostels or halfway houses and are generally run and managed by the National Probation Service, although in recent years there has been some outsourcing of certain tasks, such as staffing night cover and there are a number of independent Approved Prem- ises. According to official statistics (Ministry of Justice, 2017a) there were 13 deaths of offenders resident in Ap- proved Premises in 2016/17. The number of deaths have ranged from 9 to 15 deaths a year since 2010/11 which accounts for 2% of all deaths of offenders in the commu- nity. The majority of deaths of offenders in Approved Premises were male, while females accounted for three deaths. Approved Premises fit into our current system very uncomfortably not least because there is acute de- mand for more space. This is particularly the case for women, so much so that a woman won her case before the Supreme Court3 in 2017 on the grounds that provision of APs constitutes direct discrimination against women which is unlawful unless justified, and that the Secretary of State had shown no such justifica- tion (see R (Coll) v Secretary of State for Justice [2017] UKSC 40). At that point there were 94 APs for men, dis- tributed around England and Wales including several in London. There are only 6 APs for women, who consti- tute 5% of the prison population, and none of them is in London or in Wales. This means that women are much more likely than men to be placed in an AP which is far from their homes and communities. Deaths that occur in Approved Premises are investigated by the Prisons and Probation Ombudsman (PPO) in the same way that deaths that occur in prison are investigated. The people who die whilst residing in an AP are the only probation supervisees whose deaths are investigated by an inde- pendent investigatory body in accordance with Article 2 of the Human Rights Act 1998. In our analysis of PPO reports into deaths in APs we found that drug use was a major concern both in terms of the risk associated with problematic drug use that is common to people who are required to live in APs as well as around the poor level of drug treatment available to people in prison in the first place and then during the transition into the community (Phillips et al. 2016). We also raised con- cerns around staffing levels, especially at weekends, as well as some issues around decision making and part- nership working. In addition to the Ministry of Justice’s analysis we have conducted analysis of the raw data in research on behalf of the Equality and Human Rights Commission which focused on people who died within 28 days of leaving prison. Our analysis (Phillips et al. 2016) showed, con- firming findings from elsewhere, that the first week after leaving prison was the highest risk with 66 people dying within 28 days of leaving prison. By far the most com- mon cause of death among this cohort was a self-inflicted overdose (n = 44) and the most common of- fences were acquisitive (n = 35), an offence type which is commonly associated with problematic drug use. The ma- jority (n = 37) of those 66 deaths occurred in the first 2 weeks after release. Risk factors People under supervision have a higher mortality rate than the general population although data for England and Wales are slightly outdated. However, prevalence only tells part of the story and if concerted action can be taken to prevent suicides in the future we need a better understanding of the risks that people face that may in- crease the chances of them taking their own lives. Again, the evidence here is relatively weak. That said, drugs and alcohol use features highly amongst people who die in the community (Sattar, 2001; Binswanger et al. 2011). Table 1 Deaths of offenders in the community by gender and apparent cause, England and Wales (Ministry of Justice 2017a) 2010/11 2011/12 2012/13 2013/14 2014/15 2015/16 2016/17a NPS CRCs Total NPS CRCs Total NPS CRCs Total Males and Females 704 653 634 560 179 379 558 241 497 738 279 469 748 Self-inflicted 148 162 190 189 49 141 190 63 207 270 72 161 233 Natural Causes 238 222 240 214 75 121 196 106 135 241 124 134 258 Homicide 27 28 28 17 5 9 14 6 16 22 13 20 33 Accident 68 49 49 37 13 35 48 21 46 67 14 43 57 Other 31 42 29 25 3 12 15 1 10 11 3 11 14 Unclassifiedb 192 150 98 78 34 61 95 44 83 127 53 100 153 NPS National Probation Service; CRC Community Rehabilitation Company aMissing returns from 2 CRCs. Caution should be used when comparing with earlier periods bUnclassified deaths refer to those deaths for which a cause was unknown at the time of reporting Phillips et al. Health and Justice (2018) 6:14 Page 3 of 12 Indeed, research consistently finds that many people who have offended have poor physical and mental health, lead chaotic lifestyles and are more likely to mis- use drugs (Mills, 2004; Brooker et al. 2009; Canton, 2008; Singleton et al. 2003; Brooker and Sirdifield, 2013 and Denney et al. 2014). This is important considering mental ill health is one of the main predictors of suicid- ality (Arsenault-Lapierre, Kim and Turecki, 2004). Writ- ing about the situation in England and Wales, Cook and Borrill (2015: 255) found that the key indicators for an offender to be considered at risk of suicide were previ- ous incidents of self-harm or attempted suicide and, to a lesser extent, ‘coping skills, psychiatric treatment/medi- cation, attitude to self, childhood abuse, current psycho- logical problems/ depression, and history of close relationship problems’. Borrill et al. (2017: 12) analysed the case records of 28 people who died by suicide while under probation supervision in England and highlight ‘the complex association of events and experiences that may contribute towards pathways to suicide among pro- bation service users under supervision’. More recently still, Mackenzie, Cartwright and Borrill (2018) conducted research with seven probation clients who had attempted suicide. Their participants suggested that bereavement, loss of control over their mental state or situation, difficulties relating to their probation sen- tence, issues around trusting authorities, and an inability to disclose suicidal feelings were linked to their suicidal feelings and behaviours. Pratt et al. (2006) found that within their sample of 384 suicides that occurred within 12 months of leaving prison main risk factors ‘were in- creasing age over 25 years, released from a local prison, a history of alcohol misuse or self-harm, a psychiatric diagnosis, and requiring Community Mental Health Services (CMHS) follow-up after release from prison.’ It is clear that previous research has uncovered trends and consistent findings amongst people who die by sui- cide when under probation supervision. However, as MacKenzie et al. (2013) have argued, there is a need for more research on this important social issue because of the consistent finding that people under supervision are at higher risk of dying by suicide than other populations. In order to update Sattar’s (2001) work and to add some context to our understanding of the suicide rate of people under probation supervision we now turn to new analysis of the data that are collected by Her Majesty’s Prisons and Probation Service (HMPPS) on the number of people who die by suicide when under probation supervision. Methods In the remainder of this article we augment the Ministry of Justice’s analysis of the data on deaths of offenders under supervision to update our knowledge of the sui- cide rate amongst this population. In order to gain a better understanding of the rate of suicide amongst people under the supervision of probation providers we have conducted new analysis of official data on deaths of offenders under supervision. The data contained in the dataset was collated by HMPPS using forms completed by probation providers when someone dies in accord- ance with Probation Instruction 01/2014 (Ministry of Justice, 2014). These forms ask for basic demographic data of the offender, cause of death and brief details of what happened in the run up to the death. They are then collated and published in brief by HMPPS as discussed above. We use the data to make comparisons between this group, the general population and people who die by suicide in prison. We have followed the methodology utilised recently by Fazel et al. (2017) to calculate rate ratios between different populations. We have access to the raw data through a data sharing agreement with HMPPS in order to conduct research on behalf of the Equality and Human Rights Commission, and use this as the basis for our analysis because of the decision by HMPPS to amend their published data as a result of the non-submission of data from two CRCs as mentioned above. In order to make comparisons with other populations we have calculated the suicide rate amongst people under supervision per 100,000. We have used the num- ber of people on the caseload available from the Ministry of Justice (2016b) as this bears the strongest resemblance to measures used in both Fazel et al.’s (2017) study, Sattar’s (2001) research and suicide rates from the Office for National Statistics (Office for National Statistics, 2017). There are limitations to this approach. Firstly, there is a definitional issue. Ministry of Justice data on the deaths of offenders under supervision includes ‘category of death’. Within this category there is a label of ‘self-in- flicted’. However, this is not necessarily the same defin- ition as used by the ONS nor the same definition of suicide used by the prison service. Moreover, in many cases the cause of death recorded by probation providers is ‘Apparent - on the basis of information received’ ra- ther than having been confirmed by a coroner’s inquest verdict or death certificate. That said, this is all we have. Secondly, our use of the number of people on the case- load as a means with which to calculate suicide rates may result in inaccurate data. We are using the caseload as a proxy measure for the annual average population as described by Sattar (2001). This allows for the comparison between three groups in question: offenders in the com- munity, people in prison, and the general population. Suicide rates and rate ratios of offenders who die when in the community To make comparisons with suicide rates in other con- texts we have calculated the suicide rate amongst people Phillips et al. Health and Justice (2018) 6:14 Page 4 of 12 T a b le 2 Su ic id e ra te an d ra te ra ti o o f p eo p le d yi n g b y su ic id e u n d er su p er vi si o n ,i n p ris o n an d in th e g en er al p o p u la ti o n To ta l n u m b er o f su ic id es o f o ff en d er s u n d er su p er vi si o n (2 01 0/ 11 – 20 15 /1 6) A n n u al su ic id e ra te (o ff en d er s in co m m u n it y) / 10 0, 00 0 A n n u al su ic id e ra te (p ris o n er s) / 10 0, 00 0 (F az el et al .2 01 7) A n n u al su ic id e ra te (g en er al p o p u la ti o n ) / 10 0, 00 0 ag ed 30 – 49 (O N S) Ra te ra ti o s Ra te 95 % C I Ra te 95 % C I Su p er vi si o n /p ris o n su ic id e ra te ra ti o Su p er vi si o n /g en er al p o p u la ti o n ra te ra ti o Pr is o n /g en er al p o p u la ti o n ra te ra ti o (F az el et al .2 01 7) 16 19 11 8 99 – 13 7 83 66 – 10 0 13 .6 1. 42 8. 67 6. 1 Phillips et al. Health and Justice (2018) 6:14 Page 5 of 12 under probation supervision using the total number self-inflicted deaths between 2010/11 and 2015/16 and calculated a mean suicide rate with 95% confidence in- tervals. This allows us to compare the suicide rate of of- fenders in the community with the suicide of people in prison, as calculated by Fazel et al. (2017). Table 2 shows that the suicide rate of offenders, regardless of age or gender, is both higher than that in prison (by a factor of 1.42) and the general population (by a factor of 8.67). This reflects findings from other research looking at similar populations (Sattar 2001). Gender and suicide Suicide rates are strongly correlated with gender with death rates from suicide being four-to-five times higher for men than for women across the European Union (OECD, 2018). Thus we have calculated suicide rates and rate ratios for men and women separately. Table 3 shows that the suicide rate for men under supervision in the community is 6 times higher than the general popu- lation whilst the rate ratio between men in prison and the general population is 3.9. Meanwhile, the rate ratio between women under probation supervision and the general population is 29.2 compared with a rate ratio be- tween women in prison and the general population of 8.9. The increased risk of suicide for women in prison has long been recognised (Sandler and Coles, 2018) and our analysis suggests that the risk for women offenders in the community is even higher. Age and suicide Age is strongly correlated with suicide, with men aged 40 to 44 having the highest age-specific suicide rate at 15.3 per 100,000 (Office for National Statistics, 2017). Tables 3 and 4 shows the age-specific rates for people under supervision compared with the equivalent age- specific rates in the general population. Table 4 shows that the suicide rate for all people under probation supervision is higher than the general popula- tion. The rate ratio between men aged 30–49 is the highest with a RR of 28. In Table 5 we see that women also present a higher a risk of suicide when under proba- tion supervision with particularly high rate ratios being present amongst women aged 30–39. However, these are small numbers and so must be treated with caution. Suicide rate according to sentence type In order to ascertain a link between sentence type and suicide rate we have calculated the suicide rate amongst men and women on different sentences. Table 6 shows the suicide rate broken down by gender and sentence type. It is not possible to break this down by age group due to small numbers. It is worth noting, however, that suicide rates are higher than the general population across all sentences, and that women serving a post-release sentence appear to face a particularly high risk, as also highlighted by Sandler and Coles (2018). Ethnicity The actual numbers of people dying by suicide when broken down by ethnicity are too small for meaningful analysis of suicide rates broken down by ethnicity. More- over, the Office for National Statistics does not collect suicide rates for ethnic groups and so rate ratios with the general population cannot be calculated. However, BAME groups are over-represented in the criminal just- ice system so this does require some analysis. Thus, we have compared the proportion of suicides that occur amongst different ethnic groups with the pro- portion of people in those ethnic groups under supervi- sion. There is no data available for the breakdown of people on license/post-release supervision and so this only refers to people on a Community Order or Sus- pended Sentence Order. Table 7 shows that white men account for 97% of all suicides but only 81% of the pro- bation caseload, suggesting that they are at higher risk than other groups. All the women who died by suicide in 2015/16 on a Community Order or Suspended Sentence Order were White despite this group making up 88% of the caseload. Despite being based on small numbers this reflects Pratt et al. (2006) finding that non-white ethnicity is a protective factor. Temporal trends in the risk of suicide As discussed previously, research by ourselves (Phillips et al. 2016) and others (Pratt et al., 2006) suggests there is an increased risk of suicide and other mortality soon after release from prison. In order to ascertain whether a similar increased risk exists for people after being sen- tenced to a community sanction (both Community Or- ders and Suspended Sentence Orders) we calculated the Table 3 Suicide rate of people under probation supervision compared with suicide rate of people in prison and in general population (2010/11–2015/16) Gender Suicide rate per 100,000 offenders under supervision (2015–16) Annual suicide rate Gen pop suicide rate/100,000 aged 30–49 Rate ratios Rate 95% CI Supervision/general population rate ratio Prison/general population rate ratio (Fazel et al. 2017) Men 105 95.2–115 18.8 5.6 3.9 Women 146 115–175 5 29.2 8.9 Phillips et al. Health and Justice (2018) 6:14 Page 6 of 12 time period after sentence that a death occurred, again using 2015/16 data. Figure 1 shows that the number of deaths per week after sentence decreases slightly over a period of a year suggesting that there does appear to be a slightly increased risk of suicide in the first weeks after sentence. Day of the week For interest, we are including a table which shows the number of deaths per day of the week. We used the date of death entered on the form completed by the offender manager to calculate the number of deaths that occurred on each day of the week for the whole of 2015/16. There are no clear differences here, except for the apparent in- crease towards the end of the week. We note that Tues- day shows a high number of deaths, but there is no apparent reason for this. We are left with a number of questions as to whether this is a ‘benefits’ day, or the day on which rent is due, or whether it is simply a day when the harsh realities of the week set in. There could be many reasons for this Fig. 2. Discussion Our analysis demonstrates that the suicide rate amongst people under probation supervision, including those serving a Community Order, Suspended Sentence Order or on licence/post-release supervision, is higher than the general population. Our review of the literature high- lights some of the reasons for this disparity. English law and practice is characterised by its complexity, and by frequency of change. In the last 40 years governments (of every political persuasion) have regularly changed the rules, policy and practice relating to sentences, especially those related to the supervision of offenders in the com- munity. This means that the collection of relevant data will have been affected by changes to policy, recording practices, the advent and abolition of organisations most notably the recent part-privatisation of probation which sees different organisations (a mixture of private public) being responsible for offenders who pose different risks. The implications of this are that the data collated by Her Majesty’s Prison and Probation Service are unlikely to paint a complete picture (Phillips et al. 2017). One hun- dred and twenty seven of the 725 deaths that were re- corded in 2015/16 are classified as ‘Unknown’ and in only 88 of the 264 self-inflicted deaths recorded in 2015/ 16 was the cause of death verifiable via an inquest ver- dict or death certificate. It is likely that self-inflicted deaths will have been under-recorded because of this. This is the most significant limitation of this analysis: that some deaths will not have been recorded at all, and that others will have been recorded wrongly. Moreover, we have included self-inflicted deaths by drug overdose in our analysis as it is not always known whether there was intent to kill oneself in these circumstances which may have inflated the rate. The decision to include these deaths was made on the basis of Fazel et al.’s (2017) study showing that the majority of countries do not re- quire intent to be proven for a classification of suicide to be recorded in statistics on deaths in prison thus enab- ling comparison with their analyses. We have been unable to calculate suicide rates for dif- ferent ethnic groups, nor would we have been able to compare these with the general population due to a lack of data from ONS. Moreover, the data do not allow for calculating suicide rates according to offence because of a lack of detail in the dataset (for example, 74 of the self-inflicted deaths in 2015/16 are listed as either ‘Other Summary Offence’ or ‘Other Indictable Offence’). As ar- gued by Fazel et al. (2017) this is an area for future Table 5 Age-specific suicide rates for women under probation supervision, 2015–16 Age banda Number of deaths by suicide by people under probation supervision (2015–16) Age specific suicide rate/ 100000 on caseload Age specific suicide rate in general population/100,000 Rate ratio 18–29 9 212.01 4.2 50.48 30–39 14 414.45 4.8 86.34 40–49 10 468.82 6.8 68.94 aAge groups 18–20, 21–24 and 25–29 have been combined due to low numbers and age groups 50–59 and 60+ have been removed due to low numbers Table 4 Age-specific suicide rates for men under probation supervision, 2015/16 Age banda Number of deaths by suicide by people under probation supervision (2015–16) Age specific suicide rate/100000 on caseload Age specific suicide rate in general population/100,000 Rate ratio 21–24 21 214.61 14.8 14.5 25–29 28 238.70 17.5 13.6 30–39 86 527.41 19 27.8 40–49 66 650.05 23.5 27.7 50–59 19 449.49 21 21.4 aAge groups 18–20 and 60+ have been removed due to low numbers Phillips et al. Health and Justice (2018) 6:14 Page 7 of 12 research as it is possible that the heterogeneity of the caseload leads to a dilution of high-risk groups. These are all important areas for future investigation but are contingent upon data being available. That said, we have calculated suicide rates for people on different sentences which might, at least, be used as a proxy measure for risk of harm if not risk of reoffending. In spite of these limitations, these data provide an up- dated understanding of the suicide rate amongst people on probation. The suicide rate amongst people under probation supervision is clearly higher than that of the general population and, it seems, of people in prison. However, they do little to highlight the issues which may explain the high level of mortality observed. Whether this is to do with the process of being under supervision is not clear. Whilst quantitative data on the numbers of deaths provides useful headline figures in regard to prevalence and general risk it does little to shed light on the under- lying causes of a self-inflicted death. We cannot tell which of the risk factors identified above are most preva- lent with this group, nor does it tell us what has been happening in an offender’s life prior to them dying by suicide. Thus there is scope for making greater use of these data. Firstly, it creates the potential for data matching to make the most of other data held by proba- tion providers and other government departments. For example, Delius, the case management system that is in use by all probation providers in England and Wales should be able to provide information on the extent of an offender’s engagement with their sentence in the run up to a suicide attempt. Through the use of a specific code at the expiration of a sentence it should become possible to identify who dies by suicide and then conduct analysis on their patterns of engagement. Ana- lysis of this kind could augment Borrill et al.’s (2017) findings that missed appointments appear to be corre- lated with subsequent suicide. Similarly, OASys assess- ments and OGRS scores would enable a much greater understanding of how risk of reoffending and harm in- teracts with the risk of suicide. Other health data, as col- lected by primary or secondary healthcare providers might also shed light on the extent to which risk factors correlated with suicide in the general population, such as mental ill health, hold up within this specific population. Secondly, there is much more scope for collecting data around the life stories of many of these people who died. One approach would be to adopt that taken by Borrill et al. (2017) as mentioned above, who looked at the cases of 28 service users who took their own lives in one large probation area between 2010 and 2013. They high- light the need for further awareness-raising amongst frontline probation staff of sharing crucial information; something that would be missed with high-level analysis of Delius records. An alternative would be to conduct interviews with people who have attempted suicide whilst on probation supervision, as per Mackenzie et al. (2018), or to speak with family members who have had a relative die whilst under supervision in the community. This would reflect the methodology adopted by the PPO following a death in custody or the EHRC when con- ducting their inquiry into the deaths of adults with men- tal ill health in custodial settings (EHRC, 2015). This methodological approach would allow for the collection of data which adds considerable depth and nuance to the necessarily abstract picture presented above. These additional forms of research would add to our under- standing of the risk of suicide at an individual level which, currently, HMPPS data is unable to address. However, it is likely there are ecological factors at play which influence the risk of suicide amongst people on probation. At this stage it is important to lay out the context in England and Wales. When an offender is re- leased from prison, or receives a community order, they will be subject to supervision. Radical change was intro- duced in 2014–15, when a significant part of the previ- ously publically funded Probation Trusts was privatised. Since the Offender Rehabilitation Act 2014 came into force on 1 February 2015 the number of offenders on post-release supervision has soared. Privately run Com- munity Rehabilitation Companies now carry out the ma- jority of probation work working with low and medium risk offenders whilst a newly created National Probation Service supervises high risk offenders. It was intended that CRCs would take around 70% of the work, leaving with NPS with 30% of the caseload to supervise. In real- ity the split is nearer 60:40. This has resulted in the NPS Table 7 Proportion of suicides completed by people under supervision according to ethnicity compared with proportion of caseload belonging to ethnic group, 2015–16 Ethnic group Proportion of all suicides amongst probationers completed by ethnic group (%) Proportion of probation caseload belonging to ethnic group (%) Asian 1.5 7 Black 1.5 7 Mixed 0.7 3 White 97 81 Unknown 2 2 Table 6 Suicide rate amongst people under probation supervision by sentence type Suicide rate/100000 on caseload (2015/16) Community Order Suspended Sentence Order License/ post-release Men 142.69 103.27 128.59 Women 156.28 86.51 206.53 Phillips et al. Health and Justice (2018) 6:14 Page 8 of 12 being overstretched whilst CRCs have received less in- come than anticipated and thus have struggled to pro- vide an adequate level of service (National Audit Office, 2016; HM Inspectorate of Probation, 2017). This is the context in which we must understand the deaths of people serving sentence supervised by an in- creasingly fragmented system. In addition to the struc- tural change to probation providers, it is important to note that the prison system in England and Wales is undergoing a turbulent time. HM Inspectorate of Prisons reports have consistently pointed to increased levels of drug use, a high incidence of mental ill health and low staffing levels (HM Inspectorate of Prisons, 2017). There has been a 20% increase in violence inside prisons in England and Wales (Ministry of Justice, 2017b). When considering the effect that this may have on people on post-release supervision it raises the possi- bility of these prison based issues influencing the risk of people dying by suicide upon release. There is a real gap in provision at the point of release. There have been several negative reports on Through the Gate (TTG) services provided by CRCs (HM In- spectorate of Probation, 2016, 2017; Taylor et al., 2017) whilst Padfield’s (2017a, 2017b) research into parole un- derscores the absence of suitable provision to which prisoners can be released. A joint inspection by the HM Inspectorates of Probation and Prisons found that 15% of prisoners leave prison without accommodation to go to and reported that they ‘did not see any innovative work by CRCs to make access to accommodation easier’ (HM Inspectorate of Probation, 2016: 22). Prisons have acknowledged that they are sending people out with a tent and sleeping bag or a ‘cold weather’ mountaineering blanket (HM Inspectorate of Prisons, 2016). Moreover, the 2017 Annual Report of the Chief Inspector of Proba- tion (HM Inspectorate of Probation, 2017) highlighted the increasing number of supervision sessions carried out with offenders on the telephone which will Fig. 2 Number of deaths per day of the week, 2015–16 Fig. 1 Number of deaths per week after sentence and cumulative percentage of self-inflicted deaths, 2015–16 Phillips et al. Health and Justice (2018) 6:14 Page 9 of 12 necessarily limit the potential for good quality assess- ment and support. Whilst our data cannot say whether these gaps in service provision upon release have a dir- ect impact upon the suicide rate it is an area which re- quires further investigation through analysis of specific cases. Healthcare is a key issue when it comes to the risk of suicide and subsequent prevention. As already discussed, people on probation have greater physical and mental health needs when compared with the general popula- tion (Brooker et al. 2012). This becomes ever more important when we consider the fact that the same re- search shows that ‘offenders’ engagement with health services was incommensurate with their likely level of need’ (Brooker et al. 2009: 45). What’s more, research into the commissioning of healthcare for people under probation supervision shows that ‘only 12 per cent of Mental Health Trusts provided a service to support ap- proved premises and just 32 per cent provided clinics in probation’ (Brooker et al. 2015). The provision of health- care to people serving a community sanction is clearly inadequate and may well contribute to the high suicide rate amongst this population. Offenders in the community cannot, and should not, be subject to the same level of supervision as those in prison. Criminal justice staff will have less ability to intervene and prevent some deaths. Else- where, we have made the case for an ‘ethic of care’ (Phillips et al. 2017). It is interesting to note that the official statistics comment that Offenders under supervision in the community (other than, to an extent, those occurring in approved premises) are not in the care of NOMS in the way they are when in custody. The influence probation officers have on offenders, in terms of their health and well-being, cannot be compared meaningfully to the influence staff working in prison have in relation to deaths in custody. (Ministry of Justice 2017a: 3) Whilst it may well be true that the ability of staff to in- fluence a person on the brink of suicide is much more limited in the community, we would urge the authorities to accept that they have responsibility here too. Given what is known about the vulnerabilities of many people under community supervision, much more could be done to support them. Hence the need for a much stronger ‘ethic of care’. Our final point is about justice. There is an emerging body of evidence which demonstrates that there are a distinct set of pains associated with being on probation (Hayes 2018). Indeed, McNeill has characterised penal supervision as a Malopticon which works to degrade ra- ther than construct positive identities: ‘in the Malopticon penal subjects suffer … the pain of not being seen; at least not as they would recognize themselves’ (2018: 19, emphasis in original). We would argue that the lack of attention paid to deaths in the community in terms of poor data, lack of independent investigation, inadequate healthcare provision and a less obvious duty of care is one of the most significant forms of the civic degrad- ation which, for McNeill (2018), is part and parcel of be- ing under penal supervision. That many of these deaths appear to be either ‘missing, ignored or unimportant’ raises questions about the ways in which the state achieves justice for offenders, victims and the communi- ties in which they reside. Conclusion This article has drawn on existing literature to show that the suicide rate amongst people under statutory proba- tion supervision is higher than the general population. The article has also highlighted some of the key risk fac- tors which might explain this relatively high mortality rate. We have then conducted new analysis on national data that were collected and collated by HMPPS on the number of people who have died by suicide by when under probation supervision. Despite the limitations in the data there is a clear finding that the suicide rate across all groups under supervision is higher than the general population. Women appear to be at higher risk, relatively speaking, than men. This, we argue, may be the result of a range of factors related to the system of probation supervision and healthcare provision in England and Wales. We have also pointed to some potential avenues for future research which take both quantitative and qualitative approaches. It is only a mixed approach which will enable a better under- standing of the risk factors within different groups. Once suicides by people under probation supervision receive the attention they deserve then practitioners and policymakers will be able to implement policies which serve to reduce the suicide rate amongst this already vulnerable group. Endnotes 1These are private probation providers that were intro- duced following the implementation of the Offender Rehabilitation Act 2014. For more on the potential im- plications of these reforms, see below. 2Offender Rehabilitation Act 2014: the Act of Parliament which allowed the division of probation services into pri- vately managed companies alongside the National Probation Service: see below. 3The Supreme Court is the final court of appeal in the UK for civil cases, and for criminal cases from England, Wales and Northern Ireland. Phillips et al. Health and Justice (2018) 6:14 Page 10 of 12 Funding This research was initially funded by the Equality and Human Rights Commission. The subsequent analysis, which is presented here, has received no additional funding. Availability of data and materials As the raw data were accessed via data sharing agreement between ourselves and the Ministry of Justice we cannot deposit the data in a public depository as this would be in breach of the data sharing agreement. However, some of the data are available on the publically available Ministry of Justice website here: https://www.gov.uk/government/statistics/deaths-of-offenders-in-the- community-annual-update-to-march-2017 Authors’ contributions JP completed the analyses presented in the findings section and wrote the first draft of the interpretations. He also wrote and redrafted sections of the literature review and discussion, and revised the manuscript for intellectual content. NP wrote the initial draft of the literature review and discussion, interpreted the findings, and drafted and revised subsequent versions of the manuscript for intellectual content. LG interpreted the findings, wrote sections of the literature review and discussion and drafted and revised subsequent versions of the manuscript for intellectual content. All authors read and approved the final version of the manuscript. Ethics approval and consent to participate This research was approved by the Faculty Research Ethics Committee at Sheffield Hallam University. Reference number: 183-PHI. Consent for publication The data presented in the article were collated by the Ministry of Justice and passed to us through a data sharing agreement. We have consent to publish these analyses for the purpose of improving policy and practice around the prevention of deaths amongst offenders in the community. Competing interests The authors declare that they have no competing interests. Publisher’s Note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. Author details 1Department of Law and Criminology, Sheffield Hallam University, Heart of the Campus, Collegiate Crescent, Sheffield S10 2BQ, England. 2Faculty of Law, University of Cambridge, West Road, CB3 9DZ Cambridge, England. 3Institute of Criminology, University of Cambridge, Sidgwick Avenue, Cambridge CB3 9DA, England. Received: 16 May 2018 Accepted: 3 August 2018 References Arsenault-Lapierre, G, Kim, C, Turecki, G. (2004). Psychiatric diagnoses in 3275 suicides: A meta-analysis. BMC Psychiatry, 4(37). Biles, D, Harding, R, Walker, J (1999). The death of offenders serving community correction orders. In Trends and issues in crime and criminal justice. No.107. Canberra: Australian Institute of Criminology. Binswanger, IA, Blatchford, PJ, Lindsay, RG, Stern, MF. (2011). Risk factors for all-cause, overdose and early deaths after release from prison in Washington state. Drug and Alcohol Dependence, 117, 1–6. Borrill, J, Cook, L, Beck, A. (2017). Suicide and supervision: Issues for probation practice. Probation Journal, 64(1), 6–19. Brooker, C, & Sirdifield, C. (2013). An investigation into the prevalence of mental health disorders in an English probation population: an overview. Eurovista: Probation and Community Justice, 2(3), 154–160. Brooker, C, Sirdifield, C, Blizard, R, Denney, D, Pluck, G. (2012). Probation and mental illness. The Journal of Forensic Psychiatry & Psychology, 23(4), 522–537. Brooker, C, Syson-Nibbs, L, Barrett, P, Fox, C. (2009). Community managed offenders’ access to healthcare services: Report of a pilot study. Probation Journal, 54(1), 45–59. Brooker, C, Sirdifield, C, Ramsbotham, D, Denney, D. (2015). NHS commissioning in probation in England: On a wing and a prayer. Health and Social Care in the Community, 25(1), 137–144. Canton, R (2008). Working with mentally disordered offenders. In S Green, E Lancaster, S Feasey (Eds.), Addressing offending behaviour: Context, practice, values, (pp. 318–343). Cullompton: Willan Publishing. Cook, LC, & Borrill, J. (2015). Identifying suicide risk in a metropolitan probation trust: Risk factors and staff decision making. Legal and Criminological Psychology, 20(2), 255–266. Denney, D, Brooker, C, Sirdifield, C. (2014). Mental disorder and probation policy and practice: A view from the UK. International Journal of Law and Psychiatry, 37(5), 484–489. Equality and Human Rights Commission (2015). Preventing deaths in detention of adults with mental health conditions. Manchester: Equality and Human Rights Commission. Fazel, S, Ramesh, T, Hawton, K. (2017). Suicide in prisons: An international study of prevalence and contributory factors. The Lancet Psychiatry, 4(12), 946–952. Gelsthorpe, L, Padfield, N, Phillips, J. (2012). Deaths on probation: an analysis of data regarding people dying under probation supervision; a report for the Howard league for penal reform. London: The Howard League. Hayes D. (2018). Experiencing penal supervision: A literature review. Probation Journal, https://doi.org/10.1177/0264550518790660. HM Inspectorate of Prisons (2016). Report on an unannounced inspection of HMP & YOI Bronzefield. London: HM Inspectorate of Prisons. HM Inspectorate of Prisons (2017). HM chief inspector of prisons for England and Wales annual report. London: HM Inspectorate of Prisons. HM Inspectorate of Probation (2016). An inspection of through the gate resettlement Services for Short-Term Prisoners: A joint inspection by HM inspectorate of probation and HM inspectorate of prisons. London: HM Inspectorate of Probation. HM Inspectorate of Probation (2017). 2017 Annual Report. London: HM Inspectorate of Probation. King, C, Senior, J, Webb, RT, Millar, T, Piper, M, Pearsal, LA, Humber, N, Appleby, L, Shaw, J. (2015). Suicide by people in a community justice pathway: Population-based nested case–control study. The British Journal of Psychiatry, 207(2), 175–176. Mackenzie, JC, Cartwright, T, Borrill, J. (2018). Exploring suicidal behaviours by probation clients-a qualitative near-lethal study. Journal of Public Health, 40(1), 146–153. Mackenzie, J-M, Borrill, J, Dewart, H. (2013). Researching suicide, attempted suicide and near-lethal self-harm by offenders in community settings: Challenges for future research. International Journal of Forensic Mental Health, 12(1), 26–32. McNeill, F. (2018). Mass supervision, misrecognition and the ‘Malopticon. Punishment & Society. https://doi.org/10.1177/1462474518755137. Mills, K. (2004). Reducing drug-related deaths: The responsibility of NOMS? Probation Journal, 51(4), 407–414. Ministry of Justice (2014). Reviewing and Reporting Deaths of Offenders under Probation Supervision. PI 01/2014. London: Ministry of Justice https:// www.researchgate.net/profile/Dina_Gojkovic/post/Where_can_data_on_ suicide_in_probation_be_obtained/attachment/ 59d63733c49f478072ea4ac4/AS%3A273683585667073%401442262660075/ download/pi-01-2014-reviewing-and-reporting-deaths-of-offenders-1.doc. Ministry of Justice (2016a). Deaths of offenders in the community annual statistics bulletin 2015 to 2016. London: Ministry of Justice. Ministry of Justice (2016b). Probation: 2016. London: Ministry of Justice https:// www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/ 633168/probation-2016.xlsx [last accessed 14 May 2018. Ministry of Justice (2017a). Deaths of offenders in the community, annual update to march 2017. London: Ministry of Justice. Ministry of Justice (2017b). Safety in custody statistics bulletin, England and Wales, deaths in prison custody to march 2017, assaults and self-harm to December 2016. London: Ministry of Justice. National Audit Office (2016). Transforming rehabilitation. London: National Audit Office Retrieved from https://www.nao.org.uk/report/transforming- rehabilitation/. OECD (2018), Suicide rates (indicator), doi:https://doi.org/10.1787/a82f3459-en [accessed on 14 May 2018]. Office for National Statistics (2017). Suicides in the UK: 2016 registrations. London: Office for National Statistics. Padfield, N. (2017a) Parole Board oral hearings 2016 – exploring the barriers to release: avoiding or managing risks? Report of a Pilot Study University of Cambridge Faculty of law research paper no. 62/2017. Phillips et al. Health and Justice (2018) 6:14 Page 11 of 12 https://www.gov.uk/government/statistics/deaths-of-offenders-in-the-community-annual-update-to-march-2017 https://www.gov.uk/government/statistics/deaths-of-offenders-in-the-community-annual-update-to-march-2017 https://doi.org/10.1177/0264550518790660 https://doi.org/10.1177/1462474518755137 https://www.researchgate.net/profile/Dina_Gojkovic/post/Where_can_data_on_suicide_in_probation_be_obtained/attachment/59d63733c49f478072ea4ac4/AS%3A273683585667073%401442262660075/download/pi-01-2014-reviewing-and-reporting-deaths-of-offenders-1.doc https://www.researchgate.net/profile/Dina_Gojkovic/post/Where_can_data_on_suicide_in_probation_be_obtained/attachment/59d63733c49f478072ea4ac4/AS%3A273683585667073%401442262660075/download/pi-01-2014-reviewing-and-reporting-deaths-of-offenders-1.doc https://www.researchgate.net/profile/Dina_Gojkovic/post/Where_can_data_on_suicide_in_probation_be_obtained/attachment/59d63733c49f478072ea4ac4/AS%3A273683585667073%401442262660075/download/pi-01-2014-reviewing-and-reporting-deaths-of-offenders-1.doc https://www.researchgate.net/profile/Dina_Gojkovic/post/Where_can_data_on_suicide_in_probation_be_obtained/attachment/59d63733c49f478072ea4ac4/AS%3A273683585667073%401442262660075/download/pi-01-2014-reviewing-and-reporting-deaths-of-offenders-1.doc https://www.researchgate.net/profile/Dina_Gojkovic/post/Where_can_data_on_suicide_in_probation_be_obtained/attachment/59d63733c49f478072ea4ac4/AS%3A273683585667073%401442262660075/download/pi-01-2014-reviewing-and-reporting-deaths-of-offenders-1.doc https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/633168/probation-2016.xlsx https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/633168/probation-2016.xlsx https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/633168/probation-2016.xlsx https://www.nao.org.uk/report/transforming-rehabilitation/ https://www.nao.org.uk/report/transforming-rehabilitation/ https://doi.org/10.1787/a82f3459-en Padfield N (2017b) Parole Board oral hearings 2016–2017 – exploring the barriers to release, Stage Two of an Exploratory Study. University of Cambridge Faculty of Law Research Paper No. 63/2017. Phillips, J, Gelsthorpe, L, Padfield, N, Buckingham, S. (2016). Non-natural deaths following prison and police custody. London: Equality and Human Rights Commission. Phillips, J, Gelsthorpe, L, Padfield, N. (2017). Non-custodial deaths: Missing, ignored or unimportant? Criminology & Criminal Justice, https://doi.org/10. 1177/1748895817745939. Pratt, D, Piper, M, Appleby, L, Webb, R, Shaw, J. (2006). Suicide in recently released prisoners: A population-based cohort study. The Lancet, 368, 119–123. Pritchard, C, Cox, M, Dawson, A. (1997). Suicide and “violent” death in a six-year cohort of male probationers compared with pattern of mortality in the general population: Evidence of accumulative socio-psychiatric vulnerability. Journal of the Royal Society of Health, 117(3), 180–185. Sandler, M, & Coles, D (2018). Dying on the inside: Examining women’s deaths in prison. London: Inquest. Sattar, G (2001). Rates and Causes of Death Among Prisoners and Offenders Under Community Supervision. In Home Office research study no. 231. London: Home Office. Singleton, N, Pendry, E, Taylor, C, Farrell, M, Marsden, J (2003). Drug related mortality among newly-released offenders. London: Home Office. Solomon, E. and Silvestri, A. (2008) Community Sentences Digest. Available at: http://www.crimeandjustice.org.uk/communitysentencesdigest2008.html Taylor, S, Burke, L, Millings, M, Ragonese, E. (2017). Transforming rehabilitation during a penal crisis: A case study of through the gate services in a resettlement prison in England and Wales. European Journal of Probation, 9(2), 115–131. Webb, RT, Qin, P, Stevens, H, Mortensen, PB, Appleby, L, Shaw, J. (2011). National Study of suicide in all people with a criminal justice history. Archives of General Psychiatry, 68(6), 591–599. Phillips et al. Health and Justice (2018) 6:14 Page 12 of 12 https://doi.org/10.1177/1748895817745939 https://doi.org/10.1177/1748895817745939 http://www.crimeandjustice.org.uk/communitysentencesdigest2008.html Abstract Background Methods Results Conclusions Background What do we already know about suicide in community justice settings? Prevalence Trends and themes within English and welsh official data Risk factors Methods Suicide rates and rate ratios of offenders who die when in the community Gender and suicide Age and suicide Suicide rate according to sentence type Ethnicity Temporal trends in the risk of suicide Day of the week Discussion Conclusion These are private probation providers that were introduced following the implementation of the Offender Rehabilitation Act 2014. For more on the potential implications of these reforms, see below. Funding Availability of data and materials Authors’ contributions Ethics approval and consent to participate Consent for publication Competing interests Publisher’s Note Author details References work_j6mvxaodungixpikyn5qeh4mhi ---- Ethics & Global Politics: Vol 14, No 1 Log in  |  Register Cart Home All Journals Ethics & Global Politics List of Issues Volume 14, Issue 1 Ethics & Global Politics An open access journal Publishes research on ethics and global politics, exploring environmental protection, policy development, poverty, technology and knowledge, migration and more. Search in: This Journal Anywhere Advanced search Submit an article New content alerts RSS Citation search Citation search Current issue Browse list of issues Explore Top About this journal Journal metrics Aims and scope Instructions for authors Journal information Editorial board News & offers Editorial policies Latest articles See all volumes and issues Volume 14, 2021 Vol 13, 2020 Vol 12, 2019 Vol 11, 2018 Vol 10, 2017 Vol 9, 2016 Vol 8, 2015 Vol 7, 2014 Vol 6, 2013 Vol 5, 2012-2013 Vol 4, 2011 Vol 3, 2010 Vol 2, 2009 Vol 1, 2008 Login or register to access this feature Have an account? Login nowDon't have an account? Register for free Register a free Taylor & Francis Online account today to boost your research and gain these benefits: Download multiple PDFs directly from your searches and from tables of contents Easy remote access to your institution's subscriptions on any device, from any location Save your searches and schedule alerts to send you new results Choose new content alerts to be informed about new research of interest to you Export your search results into a .csv file to support your research Register now or learn more Download citations Choose format RIS (ProCit, Reference Manager) BibTeX RefWorks Direct Export Download citations Download citations Download PDFs Browse by section (All) Display order (Default) Published online date Page number Section A-Z Most read Most cited Ethics & Global Politics, Volume 14, Issue 1 (2021) Issue In Progress Original Article Article What Kind of Functionings Matter for Global Justice for Children? Gottfried Schweiger Article: 1873576 Published online: 19 Jan 2021 Abstract | Full Text | References | PDF (318 KB) | Permissions  610Views 0CrossRef citations Altmetric Review Article review article Beyond lockdown? The ethics of global movement in a new era Guy Aitchison Published online: 04 Mar 2021 Abstract | Full Text | References | PDF (300 KB) | Permissions  563Views 0CrossRef citations Altmetric Explore Most read articles Most cited articles Multimedia Information for Authors Editors Librarians Societies Open access Overview Open journals Open Select Cogent OA Dove Medical Press F1000Research Help and info Help & contact Newsroom Commercial services Advertising information All journals Books Keep up to date Register to receive personalised research and resources by email Sign me up Taylor and Francis Group Facebook page Taylor and Francis Group Twitter page Taylor and Francis Group Linkedin page Taylor and Francis Group Youtube page Taylor and Francis Group Weibo page Copyright © 2021 Informa UK Limited Privacy policy Cookies Terms & conditions Accessibility Registered in England & Wales No. 3099067 5 Howick Place | London | SW1P 1WG Accept We use cookies to improve your website experience. To learn about our use of cookies and how you can manage your cookie settings, please see our Cookie Policy. By closing this message, you are consenting to our use of cookies. work_j7ljgof3vvhvldtf6faugthtna ---- Cover the eyes of Lady Justice: An appeal for double‐blind peer reviewing: EMBO reports: Vol 4, No 8 Skip to Article Content Skip to Article Information work_jay62wt7bfeptgfsq775lghtly ---- Microsoft Word - 7 Dewhurst.docx Journal of Social Science Education Volume 15, Number 4, Winter 2016 DOI 10.2390/jsse-v15-i4-1449 50 Marit Dewhurst is the Director of Art Education and Assistant Professor of Art and Museum Education. Her research and teaching interests include social justice education, community-based art, anti- bias/multicultural education, youth empowerment, and the role of the arts in community development. City College of New York, 160 Convent Avenue, New York, NY 10031, Email: mdewhurst@ccny.cuny.edu Dipti Desai is an Associate Professor and Director of the Graduate Art + Education Programs. She has published widely in the area of critical multiculturalism/critical race theory in art education, contemporary art as a pedagogical site, art and social justice. She received the 2012 Ziegfield Service Award in Art Education and Specialist Fulbright Award in 2014. New York University, New York, NY 10003, Email: dd25@nyu.edu Marit Dewhurst, Dipti Desai Interviewing as a Pedagogical Tool in Arts for Social Justice: A Case Study of an Afterschool Arts Program - As a pedagogical tool interviewing can help to develop skills as creative agents for social change. - Interviewing capabilities are useful in creating art. - Interviewing can be seen as a foundation for artistic visions of the world. Purpose: The rise of out-of-school youth arts organizations, especially those dedicated to addressing social issues with young people, suggests a growing need for spaces in which we prepare young people to creatively and critically shape their communities. While the popularity of these programs is certainly positive, it does little to tell us what pedagogical lessons we might learn from how youth arts organizations approach social justice teaching in the arts. In order to understand what it takes to do social justice art education, our research team investigated the pedagogical strategies used by Center for Urban Pedagogy, an out-of-school youth arts organization. Method: Through qualitative interviews, observations, and document analyses, this case study examined the specific pedagogical strategies used by educators in the Center for Urban Pedagogy’s (CUP) Urban Investigations program to engage young people in creating art for social justice aims. Findings: Our initial findings revealed that the process of interviewing is at the center of CUP’s approach to both social engagement and art-making. According to our research, interviewing reveals hidden layers of meaning to learners, offers opportunities to visualize personal connections, and provides a means to critically and collaboratively create artwork. Keywords: Art education, ethics, civic literacy, compositional analysis, attitudes 1 Introduction In an office in Astoria Energy in New York City, five teenagers and two educators from the Center for Urban Pedagogy’s Urban Investigations program sit around the desk of the Manager; one holds a microphone, another a notepad, and another a video camera. A bit quietly at first, they ask questions: “Why did the city choose to build a power plant here? Where do you get fuel to run the generators?” As the conversation progresses and the young interviewers seem less inhibited and more pro- bing; the Manager responds in kind with complex respon- ses to their increasingly pointed questions. When the camera is finally turned off, they exit the small office and head off for a walking tour of the electricity plant. They take photographs as they walk around the plant and continue to ask questions about the various parts of the plant from transformers to generators as they head back to turn their findings into art. On paper, social justice art education—the pedagogical process that engages young people in creating art to dismantle systems of inequality—sounds promising. As many educators and artists declare, it can be a tremen- dous means through which youth can develop the critical and creative thinking skills to actively participate in the remaking of our society (Dewhurst, 2014). However, when it comes to what the actual work entails, this emancipatory approach to art education can appear more daunting. What pedagogical tools do educators in social justice arts use in their teaching? And what impact do these strategies have on the young people with whom they work, the artwork they create, and the change they aspire to create? While many school-based arts edu- cators have found successful ways to integrate social justice art-making into their curricula, those working outside of schools often have more leeway to experiment with how best to engage young people in this work. The rise of out-of-school youth arts organizations, especially those dedicated to addressing social justice justice issues with youth, suggests a growing need for spaces in which we prepare young people to creatively and critically shape their communities (Dewhurst, 2014; Smyth & Stevenson, 2003; Seidel, et. al., 2009). While the popu- larity of these programs is positive, it does little to tell us what pedagogical lessons we might learn from how youth arts organizations approach social justice teaching in the arts. Journal of Social Science Education Volume 15, Number 4, Winter 2016 ISSN 1618–5293 51 In an effort to better understand what it takes to do social justice art education, our research team set out to investigate the pedagogical strategies used by one out-of- school youth arts organization. Selected as a site based on their stated commitment to using art to engage parti- cipants in civic engagement, Center for Urban Pedagogy (CUP) has a well-recognized history of working with youth to empower them as agents of change in their own communities. In 2015, CUP’s Urban Investigations pro- gram was awarded the National Arts and Humanities Youth Program Award, the country’s highest achievement for quality programming in the arts. Through obser- vations and interviews with educators and youth working in the Urban Investigations program, we applied case study methodology to examine the specific pedagogical strategies used by educators to engage young people in creating art for social justice aims. Our initial findings revealed a complex set of philosophical stances and actual teaching tools, however, upon closer analysis of the data, it became clear that the process of interviewing is at the center of CUP’s approach to both social engage- ment and art-making. Given this finding, this paper focuses on the act of interviewing as a creative and critical strategy in social justice art education. We begin with an overview of how interviewing is used as a pedagogical tool in education and as a means of both re- search and creation in contemporary art practices today. Shifting to the case study data, we move this analysis of interviewing from the realm of professional artists to that of the youth involved in a social justice art education program. A thorough examination of the nature of the interviewing process at CUP enabled us to determine how interviewing functions as a pedagogical and aesthetic tool for the kind of critical learning, empower- ing teaching, and socially engaged art-making required of social justice arts education. 2 Interviewing as a pedagogical tool and guiding philosophy From the everyday examples of interviewing that we encounter daily—journalists interviewing a witness to an event, researchers interviewing participants, and talk show hosts interviewing celebrities—we know that inter- viewing generally consists of someone with questions (preferably critical ones), and someone with responses (preferably informed ones). But interviewing viewed through an educational lens takes on a slightly different hue; as a pedagogical tool, interviewing can serve as an important process for fostering inquiry, empowerment, and critical analysis. Because of this, interviewing and other forms of fieldwork have been used as teaching tools in several non-arts settings, including social studies classrooms and media literacy programs (Soep, 2006; Cammarota and Fine, 2008). As founder of the Educational Video Center, a youth media program, Steve Goodman (2003) describes, interviewing allows students to interact with primary sources, evaluate different infor- mation sources, and develop their own lines of inquiry: “At its most basic, the students’ inquiry begins with and spirals out of the act of questioning, as all inquiry does. But for questions to eventually lead to answers—and perhaps new questions—inquirers must learn where and how to gather information. They need to learn how to assess the reliability of the information they obtain, and finally how to interpret and integrate the new data into their existing frameworks of knowledge and experience. This is funda- mentally a social and intellectual process…. (p. 48) Recently, a number of researchers (Cahill, 2007; Cahill, & Hart, 2007; Cammarota & Fine, 2008) have also in- volved youth in conducting formal interviews as part of participatory action research projects, connecting young people with professional practices of data collection and analysis. Likewise, educators in folk arts education and geography have pointed to the multiple purposes for including interviewing and other forms of fieldwork in K- 12 schools (Job, et. al, 1999; Bowman & Hamer, 2011). In these cases, interviewing serves as an engaging teaching strategy to empower youth to participate in the living worlds around them. As one of the teaching artists at CUP states, “it's learning through experience. So they are actually investigating, rather than reading, like the traditional ways of learning.” i In addition to building basic listening, questioning, and research skills, our research highlights that interviewing connects closely to some of the key characteristics of effective social justice art education—both in theory and in practice—to facilitate an emancipatory and critical learning experience for all participants. 3 Interviewing and Contemporary Art Practices Our initial findings of the importance of interviewing in CUP’s youth arts programming inspired us to examine similar practices in the professional art world. CUP’s pedagogical approach to conduct video interviews with stakeholders in the field as an integral component of their artistic process echoes the work of many contem- porary artists who go out into the “field” to collect data— in the form of audio and video recordings, photographs, maps, etc.—to gain a better understanding of a situation or topic. Although such fieldwork is a central component of anthropology, journalism, and sociology, increased attention in recent years has focused on the connection between fieldwork in anthropology and contemporary art (Coles, 2000; Desai, 2002; Foster, 1996; Schneider & Wright, 2010) and more recently to the relationship between journalism and contemporary art (Cramerotti, 2009). Since the 1980s, artists such as Martha Rosler, Haans Haccke, Alfredo Jaar, Trevor Paglan, and Ashely Hunt, have drawn on field-based research to convey “artistic information” (Cramerotti, 2009, p. 30). Their artworks do not simply represent the information they have collected, but instead ask us to question information, thereby igniting the power of pedagogy. In comparison to journalists Cramerotti (2009) indicates, “What artists can do better is to construct a self- reflective medium, which ‘coaches’ its viewers to ask relevant questions by themselves, instead of accepting Journal of Social Science Education Volume 15, Number 4, Winter 2016 ISSN 1618–5293 52 (or refusing tout court) representations as they are proposed” (p, 30). In the words of artists, Allora and Calzadilla (2003): “art has much to offer…in its potential to provoke the public into a space of individual questioning about a parti- cular subject, about preconceived notions of truth, about forms of representation, participation, identification, etc. ... At that point it is up to each individual to decide if this self- questioning will play itself out at a political level, at a union level, at an aesthetic level, at a cultural level, or sexual level, and so on (p. 89). Invoking a more participatory approach to viewing artwork, these works of art serve as avenues for learning and active engagement with information—a far cry from more conventional passive art viewing. One example of such fieldwork-based artworks is the video, Under Discussion (2005) by Allora and Calzadilla, where conducting interviews serve as the material and medium that the artists employ in their art practice. Seeing that the discussion about the future of the island of Vieques (Puerto Rico) was deadlocked due to different interests of various constituencies, Allora and Calzadilla decided to open a space for discussion, dialogue, and debate through their artwork. The one voice that was not even part of the formal discussion regarding the future of Vieques was that of the local people who had been directly affected by decades of U.S. militarization. Lite- rally turning a table over and attaching a motor, thus making it into a functional boat, the artists hired a local boatman to take them along the coast of Vieques to interview both fisherman and local people living on this island about the changes they had experienced since the U.S. took over the island as a military base as well as what they envision for their land and communities. The video is not only a visual representation of their journey along the coast, but by drawing on the metaphor of the discussion table as a place to bring various people to the table to talk, their art project in both form and content offered a pedagogical space for questioning and thinking about who makes decisions for whom. Rachel Wetzler (2012) suggests that the move by many contemporary artists to engage in “artistic fieldwork” allows them to “investigat[e] aspects of their lives and interests by merging the apparent objectivity of documentary forms and anthropological research with a plainly subjective, flexible approach, drawing on multiple methodologies and discourses” (para # 3). Viewed from a different angle, fieldwork as a practice is a form of art— akin to the kinds of social practices popular today. Requiring face-to-face contact with people, this embo- died experience warrants learning how to read body language, therefore allowing for different ways of knowing that are connected to physical and social modes of communication (Taussig, 2008). Moving beyond con- ventional art materials and techniques, this move in social practice art includes a wider spectrum of ways of making art. “Aesthetic journalism” provides another lens to analyze and discuss the use of interviews as both artistic medium and artistic process. Aesthetic journalism involves “artistic practices in the form of investigations of social, cultural or political circumstances” (Cramerotti, 2009, p. 21). Cramerotti writes “it is rather the capacity of an art form to put our sensibility in motion, and convert what we feel about nature and the human race into concrete (visual, oral, bodily) experience” (p. 21) that makes it relevant for journalism. Although journalism and art have always had a relationship as journalists use photographs, videos, and graphic images to convey information and as a form of witnessing, images tend to be presented as objective truths and neutral knowledge. Today we know that all information conveyed through the documentary format is always mediated. Artists can then deliberately play with the ways they mediate the information they collect from fieldwork. Contemporary artists using inves- tigative methods in their practice disrupt traditional journalism’s use of mimetic aesthetic traditions as a mark of objectivity and its privileging of the visual as neutral or unbiased information. In doing so, these artists create works that challenge viewers to question the status quo and their role within it. Interviewing––and other forms of fieldwork––as a me- dium for making art, aligns with practices in social justice art education which require critical engagement with real life issues. The pursuit and organization of information that interviewing allows for makes it a prime tool for interrogating issues of inequality in ways that reveal the underlying structures of injustice. Combined with crea- tive expression, this use of interviewing can serve as a potent strategy for social justice art. Just as professional artists have drawn on interviews to develop the critical nature of their artwork, our research revealed that young people at CUP used similar tactics to create their art. 3 Research overview Working with a small research team, we—the primary investigators and authors—conducted a qualitative study of the pedagogical strategies used to create works of social justice artwork with small groups of youth involved in out-of-school programs. Comprised of two university professors with expertise in social justice art education, youth development, and contemporary art practices and one research assistant with experience as an art teacher both in and out of school settings, our research team brought a critical insider eye to the analysis of the data on learning in the Urban Investigations. Through a series of interviews and observations, our research sought to identify the specific teaching and learning tools required of social justice art education. 3.1 Participants Based in Brooklyn, New York, The Center for Urban Pedagogy (CUP) uses art and design as tools to facilitate civic engagement and impact public policy. Specifically, CUP states that their projects seek to “demystify the urban policy and planning issues that impact our commu- nities, so that more individuals can better participate in Journal of Social Science Education Volume 15, Number 4, Winter 2016 ISSN 1618–5293 53 shaping them” (welcometocup.org/About). CUP’s Urban Investigations programs match small groups of teens with a teaching artist to examine a real life issue about how the city works from multiple perspectives in order to cre- ate a work of art for the public. Previous Urban Investigation programs have explored issues such as food distribution, high school application processes, waste treatment systems, and internet ownership (welcome tocup.org/Projects/ UrbanInvestigations). Each multi- week investigation begins with a key question, for example, “Where does our water come from?” “Where does our garbage go?” Students and teachers together launch their exploration of the key questions first by reading both academic and popular articles that provide a foundational understanding of the issue at hand. Through discussions and art-making activities, youth participants and adult staff generate a list of potential stakeholders to interview for additional information. Equipped with professional recording equipment and basic training in interviewing techniques that covers developing questions, asking follow-up questions, and active listening, youth participants conduct interviews of policy makers, local government officials, community leaders, and engaged citizens. Youth then work closely with the teaching artists to turn the content and experi- ences of their interviews into works of art for public distribution. These investigations have resulted in short videos, posters, and websites for distribution across the city (and beyond). Our research project focused on two separate Urban Investigations that took place over three months during the summer of 2011: one investigation focused on learning about the infrastructure of electricity in the city and the second focused on the NYC Fair Share policy. Youth participants for the Power Trip project that investigated the infrastructure of electricity in NYC inclu- ded four high school aged youth, one adult lead teaching artist and one adult assistant teaching artist. As they researched how energy flows through the city, parti- cipants in this Urban Investigation met with officials at a local utility company headquarters, an upstate trans- mission monitoring center, and visited several power plants. Prioritizing primary source data collection over today’s typical turn to the internet enables youth to develop public speaking, inquiry, contextualizing, and professional communication skills. In addition, these experiences put youth in direct conversation with the real life decision makers that are connected to their own urban communities--a move that engages young people directly with those in power. Youth and the adult facilitators then used information gathered during these interactions to create a multi-lingual poster and book that has been distributed by local libraries, at several formal presentations throughout the city, and received special mention from a professional design association (CUP Power Trip website, 2015). Following a similar trajectory, participants in the Share, Where? project included ten high school aged youth from the Bronx, one adult lead teaching artist, and one adult assistant teaching artist who “teamed up to find out how New York City decides where to put the burdensome, smelly, and dangerous facilities that make the city run—but nobody wants in their backyards,” (CUP Share, Where? website, 2015). Over the course of the Share, Where? project participants met with sanitation workers, environmental justice advocates, an anti-waste facility neighborhood group, and policymakers behind the Fair Share legis- lation. Drawing on their research with these primary sources, the team of youth and teaching artists created a visually-rich book that has been distributed and used by local community groups to educate people about the Fair Share policy. Resulting creative design products from each Urban Investigation continue to be shared through CUP’s ongoing community-building and policy education programs. 3.2 Data Collection & Analysis The qualitative methods of interviews, participant obser- vations, and document analysis enabled us to collect significant data about the pedagogical strategies at play in the two Urban Investigations. The collected data inclu- ded interviews with each educator, assistant educator, and almost all of the youth participants, observations of the working sessions, and document analysis of the training guides, artwork produced, and CUP’s program literature. This rich array of data allowed us to triangulate our findings as we compared the responses of the teaching artists with those of the youth participants and the documents and artwork that emerged from their process. To analyze this data, we drew upon grounded theory methodology (Glaser & Strauss, 1967) to use an iterative coding strategy in which we elicited emic codes from the data and then layered in etic coding to compare the data with dominant literature in social justice art education. The findings that emerged from this qualita- tive process highlight the important role of interviewing at CUP. The following discussion of these findings points to the many ways in which interviewing can be used as an effective pedagogical and philosophical tool in social justice art education. 4 Findings Throughout our analysis of the nature of social justice art education at CUP, the process of interviewing rose again and again as a core pedagogical strategy. A closer analysis of this tool reveals that it functions as both as a specific teaching and learning tool and as a philosophical guide to shape the very curriculum at CUP. In our research, it became clear that interviewing is a far more complex arts learning activity than first assumed, contributing to the criticality and shifting power dynamics required of effec- tive social justice art education. To better understand the multifaceted role that interviewing plays at CUP and, potentially in social justice art education broadly, we identify the key contributions it fostered among youth and adult participants. Journal of Social Science Education Volume 15, Number 4, Winter 2016 ISSN 1618–5293 54 4.1 Revealing what is real (but often hidden) in the world Including fieldwork as part of the artistic process allows students to contextualize the knowledge they are learning and connect it to the real world (Fuller, 2006). In the case of social justice based art education it helps students to understand how our society is structured and who makes decisions that impact our daily lives, but also to question how and who created these structures. As described above, CUP’s Urban Investigations prioritize interviewing as a tool for conducting primary source research as much of the experience is based on what one teaching artist described as “doing actually real inves- tigation.” This real-world connection is a vital component of the process. As one teaching artist explains, “they are learning how to ask the questions and they are feeling empowered that way. ... It's like ok, this is information that we actually got, it's not in a textbook. You know we've read a few things and we are actually going and asking these questions. I think that's the really exciting thing that the CUP program does…. I read this in a textbook, but now we are actually going, you know to this place that it talked about. We are going to actually experience this and then report back on our views of this experience. The emphasis on “actually” throughout this reflection highlights how unique and transformative it is to have direct engagement with information for both youth and teaching artists. As they directly interact with information through their interviews, youth are participating in a form of experien- tial education, a kind of learning with a constructivist view of knowledge. Experiential learning calls for an un- derstanding of knowledge as a fluid process that requires negotiation, flexibility, learning and unlearning, and is always subjective (Duckworth, 1987; Dewey, 1980). As one of the teaching artists indicates, “most of the things we learn together when we are in interviews talking to people in the field and we learn things that we might not have thought of before and this may lead us to change our ideas.” This fluidity echoes the process of making art in which artists reiterate ideas until they are satisfied with a final product. In this way, the interviewing process and the art-making process provide parallel avenues to revisit and re-interpret information as youth deepen their understanding of the topic under study. As this teaching artist continued, “it's challenging because they are not used to doing things like [CUP] do[es]....So we are thinking differently, we are doing these puppets or we are doing this drawing or these collages and they make sense to whatever we are doing but, you know, it's, you taking information in a different way. The interviews in the Urban Investigations, much like the work of contemporary artists, provide young artists with opportunities for direct engagement with primary source information. Similarly, these interviews open up spaces to navigate the messiness and often-shifting nature of information about civic and social issues. In doing so, they expose the complex reality of the structures that shape our society––particularly those structures that are hidden or opaque to casual observation. As a tool of making art, interviews serve as an important tactic to give realistic shape to the artwork that young people seek to create. 4.2 Visualizing personal connections As both education scholarship (Duckworth, 1987) and practical experience tell us, to truly understand a con- cept, it is useful to experience it firsthand. Such primary experiences enable learners to forge their own connec- tions to the topic at hand, thereby connecting the topic to their own lives. In other words, by experiencing some- thing directly, learners can, as one teaching artist noted, “make it their own.” At CUP, the process of interviewing connects youth directly to the civic structures they are exploring. It is an opportunity for youth to experience–-in a physical, temporal, spatial, and affective manner–– environments and conversations that may have been previously off-limits. For example, it is only because the youth were investigating how we get our electricity that they were allowed to visit the power stations and sub- stations in New York City. This rare access provided an immediate experience that made real the connections between the different stakeholders involved in delivering the city’s electricity. When we make systems of power personally relevant, they become easier to identify and address. Through the interview process, the youth participants learned about the social and economic dimensions of power and power usage across social class lines and connected it to their own lives. One youth participant asked the follow up question, “What you’re describing, would my family be able to benefit from an energy program like this?” Another youth made an important observation about where power plants are located in the city in terms of social class: “Well, it’s mostly in poor neighborhoods, like Hunt’s Point, where there’s power plants, sewage treat- ment and people there are getting sick.” A youth video- taping the interview, immediately agreed, “Yeah I live in Hunt’s Point, there’s 15,000 trucks that frequent the area [for deliveries and shipping]”. Writing about the impor- tance of situated learning where education starts “from the students’ situation,” social justice education scholar, Ira Shor (1992) asserts that this “increases their ability to participate [as active learners], because they can begin critical reflection in their own context and their own words” (p. 45). Based on what they had learned from the interviews at the power plant students then began to create a visual map of how power reaches our homes from the power plants. They worked collectively on this mapping, each one taking a different section to make legible through images the invisible structure of power in our city. Con- ceptual mapping, commonly known as brainstorming has been used in education to illustrate complex connections between ideas (Powell, 2010). Visual mapping is a way to locate ourselves not only physically, but psychologically, Journal of Social Science Education Volume 15, Number 4, Winter 2016 ISSN 1618–5293 55 culturally, and socially. Contemporary artists have pushed the boundaries of mapping to capture these other dimensions, such as emotions, memory, and the body, in what Powell (2010) calls the “metaphorical powers of maps” that allow for a multisensory experience (p.539). Social justice education, as scholars have emphasized, needs to begin where students are and with what they know (Freire, 1970; hooks, 1994; Shor, 1992). To do so, educators need to provide the tools to visualize how these structures of inequity relate to their students (and their own) lives. From this space of personal under-stan- ding educators can then move students to think critically about the systemic nature of these inequities and how institutions can play a role in maintaining, managing, and also changing these inequities. 4.3 Thinking critically, creating critically Interviewing in the field allows students to learn about and appreciate different perspectives on a topic, which in turn allows them to think out their own values. “Field- work enables students to develop their understanding of different perspectives on social, political or ecological issues, enabling them to clarify and justify their own values whilst learning to acknowledge and respect other people’s values” (Job, Day, & Smith, 1999). As one of the teaching artists explained, peeling back to uncover injus- tice is important as many of the people interviewed at the power plant spoke to the connection between low income neighborhoods, poverty, and racism but in diffe- rent ways, which provided a more complex picture of the issues: “I'm just saying for example, in this project where the, the idea that when facilities were dumped into poor neighborhoods and minority, like Polish neighborhoods or here in the Bronx or in Brooklyn or Queens, whatever there is racism involved in those decisions but also well, you know the land is cheaper there and there are other things that makes it more complex than just on the surface. So I try to bring those issues to the table too so the students can think about that too. So it's not like hey, these people are bad, you know what I mean. So it's not one sided and too flat of an argument. So I try to bring the more complexity to it. Which is the hard thing. But yeah, that is one of the challenges. One of the reasons CUP uses interviews is to unearth the social structures and processes that are invisible in our daily lives but play a major role in shaping our daily life. (i.e., where does power come from?). By investi- gating these invisible structures and then reporting back what they have learned through artworks, youth shift to become advocates. They move from learning how to ask questions in order to elicit information about social structures and policies to analyzing the information they have collected from the interviews to create artworks that serve as education tools. The final design products–– be they posters, short videos, or visually-rich books–– teach the public about complex structures that are typically invisible and how these structures can affect our lives. As one youth participant recalls, “we went to this power plant and we've never been to a power plant and we didn't really know what it did, we weren't even exactly sure what we were looking for. But after the first three interviews we were able to kind of understand that our question was actually like, what is this power plant and who are the people involved in making these decisions in terms of this (plant). And I'm not even sure if that is something that we could of like figured out in the beginning, like, how to narrow down the question or how to make it more successful.” Through conducting and translating interview data into visual forms, youth participants managed to convey com- plicated information in more easy-to-access formats. Just as the interviews themselves revealed the complexity of city systems, the artwork that resulted from these interviews extended that knowledge to a wider audience. 4.4 Making art collaboratively Collaborative learning, where the teacher and student learn together is a key element of any form of social justice education (Freire, 1970; hooks, 1994). Such non- hierarchical learning creates opportunities for teachers and students to learn from each other, to take turns as the expert, and to change the conventional lines of power that tend to hold the teacher or adult in a position of greater authority and agency. Found often in out-of- school youth arts programs, collaboration requires flexibility and willingness to allow a project to unfold organically. As Goodman (2003) writes, “To effectively teach students across the field of their experiences, educators must sometimes follow, sometimes lead, and sometimes work with them side by side. No lesson plan can fully map this out” (p. 54). As a platform for colla- borative learning, interviewing is unique in that it cannot be pre-scripted, reveals new perspectives to all parti- cipants in the moment, and requires a back-and-forth dialogue between the interviewer and interviewee; in short, there is an important element of surprise that opens up spaces for new kinds of learning. Perhaps the most obvious way in which interviewing fosters collaborative learning is that neither the adult educators nor the youth participants know what the interviewee will say. One teaching artist described this element of mystery in this collaborative process: “I tell them all of the time, ‘Hey, we are doing this together, I don't know the answers.’ And you know we write the questions, … we prepare for interviews, so they [the youth participants] come up with a lot of questions, we [all] edit them down and organize them and so forth. So, I say, ’guys that's a great question, I don't know the answer, let's find out when we talk to this person or that person.’ Because the teaching artists and youth participants are both meeting the interviewees for the first time, they are hearing new information together and learning to make sense of it simultaneously. In this way, the process of interviewing results in a learning context in which every- one involved is experiencing a sense of discovery. As one teaching artist stated, “the nice thing is that we are Journal of Social Science Education Volume 15, Number 4, Winter 2016 ISSN 1618–5293 56 discovering this together. So I feel like I'm on the same playing field [as the youth participants].” Echoing this idea of the shared “playing field”, in CUP’s Urban Investigations, the interview task provides an unusual opportunity for youth and adult teaching artists to work as partners in art-making. Beyond the fact that they both engage in a parallel process of discovery, the process of developing, conducting, analyzing, and trans- lating the interview into a work of art is also collabo- rative. This collaboration happens on multiple levels, as one teaching artist describes: “We work together, it's a collaboration. It's a collaboration of different levels. First is with your students, then it's with people up top [CUP directors] and sometimes we bring graphic designers to help us too. So, it's a collaboration of different levels….It's like a diamond sort of thing where you basically have to carve it. So it takes different levels to get there. So it's a collaboration of different levels. You go back and forth with the student a lot, all the time. … we [teaching artists] send them [youth participants] the proofs so they can actually see it before we even publish it…. So yeah, it's a long process. Throughout this collaboration, youth and adults each bring their own expertise to the table to work together to prepare for, conduct, analyze, and transform an interview into a work of art; the youth participants generated ideas and questions based on their own experiences and the teaching artists shared their technical skills in inter- viewing, and art and design. When learning shifts to be collaborative—or, as Youth Radio’s Lissa Soep (2006) writes, a kind of “collegial pedagogy”—the experience is likely to empower both the youth and the adults in- volved. Because both parties can contribute as full part- ners in the design, coordination, and analysis of the inter- view, the process engenders a sense of group ownership over the project. As one teaching artist stated, the youth are empowered because they “own the project that they are creating and it's not like in some ways ok, they're [the youth] here because I'm saying we're doing a project on energy. I'm giving them that prompt and telling them what we are doing but in every other way like they get to make a lot of decisions. This shared decision-making is a key component of the entire process—from the initial interview through the creation of the final work of art. The same teaching artist continued this sentiment: “I want them to feel like they are teaching me something too and like they are learning something that I haven't thought of. I think that is important that it feels like a really collaborative experience in terms of, like, I'm the art teacher and I'm teaching you how to shape correctly or draw something that looks like something in the real world. You know, it's more like I'm teaching us both how to get information from the real world and apply that to our lives. Which is a hard kind of organic thing that happens as you do it. In talking about the work of youth and adult producers at Youth Radio, Soep (2006) describes that “With collegial pedagogy, mentoring adults offer access to equipment, expertise, in-the-moment advice, creative collaboration, and crucially, a network of relationships with outlets for young people’s work” (p. 38). Whereas many youth arts organizations have created opportunities for entirely youth-led projects, the shift to a collegial pedagogy, where youth and adults work as partners, allows for an authentic power-sharing in the art-making process. This collaborative process also facilitates opportunities for youth and adults to learn together. “The beauty of this collaboration” one teaching artist noted, is that “it's not like I'm telling them what do it's okay as what can you bring to the table and what can I bring to the table and we start from there.” This back-and-forth was evident in our observations as we noted constant discussion between youth and adults as they worked together to make artistic decisions about their final artworks. At times working all on one sheet of paper to draw out a plan, it was clear that the interviews provided a common ground from which each participant—be it a young person or an adult teaching artist—could contribute actively and with authenticity. While this kind of collaborative learning may sound elegant in theory, it is important to note that shared decision-making and true collegial pedagogy is not with- out its challenges. To truly share the decision-making process with youth participants, teaching artists must give up some of their own power and control over the curriculum and over the final product. This can result in a sense of what one teaching artist described as “uncer- tainty” as they worry, “what are we going to make in the end?” Yet, this uncertainty is actually a critical part of the process as it opens up a unique space in which youth and adult teaching artists come to create a work of art collaboratively. One teaching artist captured this tension in describing her reflections about the process: “We don't go in knowing what we are going to make. … our whole brainstorming process was the challenging part for me because I am just, like, nervous about wanting to make sure that [the project] gets done. Also, on the flip side... I'm not the one who is creating the project. So, this goes back to it being a collaborative work project. Like, I'm not the one creating it so it's not really fair for me to say, ‘oh I have an idea and I want you guys to create this.’ That's not what it is. It's the students, they have to come up with what they want to see, what they envision, how they can reflect what they've learned throughout the summer into some sort of print form. Such ongoing negotiation of the balanced contribu- tions of both youth and adult participants throughout the Urban Investigations highlighted how interviewing can be a useful tool to encourage collaborative art-making. 5 Final thoughts In writing about the role of teaching, Maxine Greene (2003) reminds us that it “is a matter of awakening and empowering today’s young people to name, to reflect, to Journal of Social Science Education Volume 15, Number 4, Winter 2016 ISSN 1618–5293 57 imagine, and to act with more and more concrete res- ponsibility in an increasingly multifarious world” (p. 72). In our research with the Center for Urban Pedagogy’s Urban Investigations youth program, it is clear that the pedagogical tool of interviewing can play a useful role in providing a range of opportunities for young people to develop their skills as creative agents for social change. Through CUP’s Urban Investigations, youth participants learned how to compose appropriate and investigative questions, how to ask those questions to stakeholders with real access to power, how to analyze the responses, and how to translate the information they learned into a creative platform for a wider audience. In addition to being useful skills in many professions, these interviewing capabilities are particularly useful in creating art. Aligned with the work of contemporary artists, this research- based art practice includes observational skills, data collection and analysis, visual mapping of ideas, inter- viewing skills, listening skill, question posing, commu- nicating skills, technical skills of videotaping, drawing, and photography. Interviewing, as an artistic tool allows youth to use their art to ask probing questions that make us think anew, thereby challenging the status quo. Echoing Greene’s words, the youth participants used interviewing as a means through which they learned to ask questions about the world around them and then to share what they learned with a wider audience. As such, interviewing serves as an important process of art making, another addition to the post-modern principles of art and design. At CUP, our research highlighted how interviewing can be seen not only as an effective teaching tool, but also as the foundation upon which young artists build their understanding and artistic visions of the world as they see it and the world as they would like it to be. References Allora and Calzadilla (2003). Interview with Sophie McKinlay in Tate Modern, Common Wealth Exhibition Catalogue. London: Tate Publishing. Bowman, P. and Hamer, L. (2011). Through the Schoolhouse Door: Folklore, community, curriculum. Logan, UT: Utah State University Press. Cahill, C. (2007). Doing research with young people: Participatory research and the rituals of collective work. Children’s Geographies, 5(3), 297-312. Cammarota, J. & Fine, M. (2008). Revolutionizing Education: Youth participatory Action research in motion. New York: Taylor & Francis. Cahill, C. & Hart, R. (Eds.). (2007). Rethinking the Boundaries of Civic Participation by Children & Youth in North America. Children, Youth and Environments, 17(2). Cramerotti, A. (2009). Aesthetic Journalism: How to inform with informing. Bristol and Chicago: Intellect. Center for Urban Pedagogy. (2015). Share, Where? Accessed on February 3, 2015 at welcometocup.org/ Projects/UrbanInvestigations/ShareWhere Center for Urban Pedagogy. (2015). Power Trip Accessed on February 3, 2015 at welcometocup.org/Projects/ UrbanInvestigations/PowerTrip Coles, A ( Ed.) (2000). Site-specificity: The Ethnographic turn. (de-,dis-ex.,Vol 4) London: Black Dog Publishing. Desai, D. (2002). The Ethnographic Move in Contemporary Art: What does it mean for Art Education. Studies in Art Education, 43(4), 307-323. Dewey, J. (1980). Art as experience. New York: Perigee Books. Dewhurst, M. (2014). Social Justice Art: A framework for activist art pedagogy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Education Press. Duckworth, E. (1987). “The Having of Wonderful Ideas” and Other Essays on Teaching and Learning. New York: Teacher’s College Press. Foster, H. (1996). Artist as Ethnographer. In The return of the Real. Cambridge: MIT Press. Freire, P. (1970). Pedagogy of the oppressed. New York, NY: Herder and Herder. Glaser, B. G., & Strauss, A. L. (1967). The discovery of grounded theory; strategies for qualitative research. Chicago, IL: Aldine Pub. Co. Goodman, S. (2003). Teaching youth media: a critical guide to literacy, video production & social change. New York: Teachers College Press. hooks, b. (1994). Teaching to transgress: education as the practice of freedom. New York: Routledge. Job, D. Day, C. & Smyth, A. (1999) Beyond the Bike sheds: fresh approaches to fieldwork in the school locality. Sheffield. Geographical Association. Powell, K. (2010). Viewing Places: Students as Visual Ethnographers. Art Education, 63(6), 45-53. Taussig, M. (2008). Ethnography and Art at Sydney Biennale. Retreived on March 19, 2014 from digiethno.wordpress.com/2008/07/04/mick-taussig- discuses- ethnography-and-art-at-sydney-biennale-18- june-2008/ Schneider, A. & Wright, C. (2010). Between art and anthropology: Contemporary ethnographic practice. London: Bloomsbury Academic. Seidel, S., Tishman, S., Winner, E., Hetland, L., & Palmer, P. (2009). The qualities of quality: Understanding excellence in arts education. Cambridge, MA: Project Zero. Shor, I. (1992). Empowering Education: Critical Teaching for Social Change. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press. Journal of Social Science Education Volume 15, Number 4, Winter 2016 ISSN 1618–5293 58 Smyth, L. & Stevenson, L. (2003) "You Want to Be a Part of Everything": The Arts, Community, & Learning. A Report from the September 2003 Forum of the Arts Education Partnership. Washington, DC: Arts Education Partnership. Soep, E. (2006). Youth Mediate Democracy. National Civic Review, 95(1), 34-40. Wetzler, R. (2012). The Art of Fieldwork. Rhizome Editorial. Retrieved on September 19, 2013 from rhizome.org/editorial/2012/feb/2/artist-ethnographer/ Endnote i In this paper, we draw upon data from our interviews and observations of educators and participants involved in two Urban Investigations at the Center for Urban Pedagogy. Excerpted quotations were recorded and transcribed by our research team. To maintain confidentiality, we will refer to the interviewee’s role within CUP as the primary identifier for each data point. work_jcc5twzinvhzdbx2h6kh6zf72y ---- Journal of Contemporary Criminal Justice 2014, Vol. 30(3) 333 –352 © 2014 SAGE Publications Reprints and permissions: sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav DOI: 10.1177/1043986214536660 ccj.sagepub.com Article Genocide, Justice, and Rwanda’s Gacaca Courts Hollie Nyseth Brehm1, Christopher Uggen2, and Jean-Damascène Gasanabo3 Abstract More than one million people participated in the 1994 genocide against the Rwandan Tutsi. How did Rwanda, whose criminal justice infrastructure was decimated by the genocide, attempt to bring the perpetrators to justice? In this article, we provide the first analysis of the outcomes of the gacaca courts, a traditional community-based justice system that was greatly modified to address crimes of genocide. After briefly reviewing the creation of the National Service of Gacaca Jurisdictions, we explain the court process. Then, we present an overview of the outcomes of the courts with a focus on the specific sanctions given to those found guilty. This article provides the first systematic analysis of these sanctions, contributing both an empirical overview and new insights into how Rwanda attempted to bring justice to the many citizens who took part in the genocidal violence. We conclude by briefly highlighting some successes and failures of the gacaca system and its broader lessons for justice in other contexts. Keywords genocide, restorative justice, Rwanda, punishment, courts On April 6, 1994, the plane carrying the President of Rwanda and the President of neighboring Burundi was shot down as it prepared to land in the capital of Rwanda. The crash killed the plane’s occupants immediately, and within hours, targeted killing 1University of Minnesota, Minneapolis, USA 2The Ohio State University, Columbus, OH, USA 3Research and Documentation Center on Genocide, Rwandan National Commission for the Fight Against Genocide, Rwanda Corresponding Author: Hollie Nyseth Brehm, Department of Sociology, The Ohio State University, 238 Townshend Hall, 1885 Neil Avenue Mall, Columbus, OH 43210, USA. Email: nyset005@umn.edu 536660CCJXXX10.1177/1043986214536660Journal of Contemporary Criminal JusticeNyseth Brehm et al. research-article2014 by guest on September 21, 2014ccj.sagepub.comDownloaded from mailto:nyset005@umn.edu http://ccj.sagepub.com/ 334 Journal of Contemporary Criminal Justice 30(3) of Tutsis and those associated with them began. Members of the government had deliberately engendered animosity between the two main ethnic groups—Hutu and Tutsi—which had become politicized and polarized during Belgian colonialism. Just a few months later, over 1,050,000 people were dead (Center for Conflict Management of the National University of Rwanda, 2012). To put this number in perspective, these 1,050,000 people comprised approximately 14% of Rwanda’s 7.5 million1 inhabitants, a rate of killing 2,800 times higher than the current U.S. homicide rate of 5 per 100,000. Government leaders were largely responsible for the planning and execution of genocide. Yet, it is also well documented that priests, doctors, nurses, judges, and even human rights activists took part in the violence by murdering their neighbors, looting houses, destroying property, and raping women (Center for Conflict Management of the National University of Rwanda, 2012; Fujii, 2009; Hatzfeld, 2008; Mamdani, 2001; Straus, 2006). Overall, more than one million perpetrators participated in the genocide; and as new government leaders debated how to rebuild the country, an important part of the conversation concerned holding these partici- pants accountable. How has Rwanda, whose criminal justice system was destroyed by the genocide, attempted to bring the massive number of perpetrators to justice? This article offers a first look at some of the outcomes of the gacaca courts, a traditional community-based justice system that was modified to address crimes of genocide. We briefly explain the creation of the National Service of Gacaca Jurisdictions before discussing how these courts functioned in law and in practice. Next, we draw on court records to present an overview of the outcomes of these courts. We focus particularly on the sanctions given to different groups of perpetrators, which have yet to be systematically analyzed. Finally, we briefly place the successes and failures of the gacaca courts in context, discussing the system’s lessons for transitional justice and other settings. Transitional Justice: Responding to Genocide Due in part to the magnitude and severity of the crimes, transitional justice responses to genocide often occur at both the local and international levels. Internationally, for- mal trials have only been legitimized as appropriate responses to genocide and similar atrocity crimes since World War II. While prosecution was considered after the Armenian genocide and for war crimes committed during World War I (Bass, 2000; Heberer & Matthaus, 2008), the 1945 Nuremberg trials are widely recognized as the key precedent for international trials for mass atrocity.2 After the Nuremberg Tribunal closed, members of the newly formed United Nations began discussing the possibility of a permanent international tribunal. Due in part to Cold War rivalries, however, that court (known today as the International Criminal Court) was not yet in existence when genocide occurred in Rwanda. Instead, in November 1994, the United Nations Security Council passed a resolu- tion that created the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda (ICTR). The mandate of this ad hoc tribunal was to try the Rwandans deemed most responsible for the geno- cide. The ICTR held its first trial in Arusha, Tanzania, in 1997 and handed down the by guest on September 21, 2014ccj.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://ccj.sagepub.com/ Nyseth Brehm et al. 335 world’s first conviction by an international court for the crime of genocide 1 year later. As of 2014, the tribunal has completed 75 cases (ICTR, 2013b). While the ICTR was heralded as a milestone in international criminal justice, it lacked both the mandate and the capacity to try even a fraction of those who partici- pated in the genocide. Instead, Rwandan leaders were faced with the task of deciding how to hold people accountable while simultaneously facilitating reconciliation. The mass public participation in the violence, as well as the country’s traditional focus on restorative justice, led many observers to recommend forming a truth commission (Clark, 2010).3 In fact, at the insistence of international donors and non-governmental organiza- tions (NGOs), a truth commission operated in Rwanda just 1 year before the genocide to investigate alleged human rights violations by the government (Bornkamm, 2012). Rwandan leaders considered forming another truth commission after the genocide but ultimately rejected this approach on the grounds that it would not adequately punish those who had taken part in the violence (Clark, 2010). Thus, while some of the key orchestrators of the genocide would be tried at the ICTR, a mechanism was still needed to respond to the violence within Rwanda. Rwanda’s Response: The Gacaca Courts As discussions about a large-scale response to the genocide continued, the new Rwandan government—comprised mainly of members of the Rwandan Patriotic Front (RPF) rebel army that stopped the genocide—was beginning to punish suspected per- petrators. In 1994 and 1995, government officials searched for people suspected of participating in the genocide and transported them to Rwandan prisons (Bornkamm, 2012; Clark, 2010). An estimated 120,000 people were brought to facilities that were built to hold 45,000 people. The 19 prisons in Rwanda were thus operating at over 200% capacity, with the vast majority of the incarcerated awaiting genocide trials (International Center for Prison Studies, 2013). Just as the prison infrastructure was inadequate to handle the sheer number of geno- cide participants, the existing judicial system was ill-suited to manage the newly incar- cerated suspects or the many other suspected genocidaires who were not in prison. Moreover, many lawyers and judges had been killed during the genocide or had fled the country. In November 1994, there were only 12 prosecutors and 244 judges in Rwanda, compared to 70 prosecutors and 758 judges in Rwanda before 1994 (Gacaca Report Summary, 2012). Even at full capacity, however, the existing Rwandan justice infrastructure would have been straining at the seams in responding to claims against over one eighth of the nation’s population. In response, multiple international NGOs donated money, time, and other resources to help the Rwandan national courts train new judges and lawyers. Many new legal personnel were indeed trained (estimates in 1996 included 210 prosecutors and 841 judges), and the national court system began hearing cases related to the genocide (Gacaca Report Summary, 2012). Yet, by 2000, only a few thousand cases had been processed (Bornkamm, 2012; Clark, 2010).4 by guest on September 21, 2014ccj.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://ccj.sagepub.com/ 336 Journal of Contemporary Criminal Justice 30(3) The government of Rwanda thus turned to a different mechanism that combined retributive and restorative justice in 2001—the gacaca courts. Gacaca courts date back to before Rwanda was colonized (Bornkamm, 2012). Gacaca means “grass” in Kinyarwanda, and, as the name implies, the hearings were traditionally held outside in empty markets, school yards, and other public places within each community. In an ideal hearing, defendants would confess their crimes, express remorse, ask for forgiveness, provide restitution, and then offer food and drink to all parties as a symbol of reconcili- ation (Vandeginste, 1999). This traditional method of dispute resolution, which bears a close correspondence to the principles of restorative justice (Drumbl, 2002), had been established as an officially sanctioned court system for common crimes since the 1940s. After the genocide, however, the institution changed significantly (for detailed information, see Bornkamm, 2012; Clark, 2010; Jones, 2009), to the dismay of critics who lament the shift from a community-based informal system to a formal institution with close ties to the state (Waldorf, 2006). Government leaders decided that the modi- fied gacaca courts, called inkiko gacaca but shortened here to gacaca, were to be organized at local levels throughout the country. Its goals would be simultaneously punitive (e.g., fighting impunity) and restorative (e.g., contributing to national recon- ciliation),5 and the courts would have jurisdiction over genocide and crimes against humanity committed between October 1, 1990, and December 31, 1994.6 As there were too few lawyers or judges for the trials, and as the courts were intended as community courts, lay members of the community would serve as judges (inyangamugayo). In October 2001, the first round of elections for gacaca judges began. Legal training was not required to serve as a judge. Instead, judges were selected on the basis of their commitment to justice, truth, and a “spirit of sharing.” They were required to be 21 years or older, have no previous criminal convictions, and could not have been serving in a government or political leadership role. They also could have never been suspected of committing crimes against people during the genocide (Organic Law, 40/2000). More than 250,000 male and female judges were elected, and in April 2002, the elected judges underwent training. Finally, on June 18, 2002, the first pilot phase of the gacaca began.7 Court Procedure The judgment phase of the courts began in March 2005. Suspects were divided into three categories (Organic Law, 13/2008), as defined in the Appendix. In brief, Category 1 was reserved for planners or organizers of the genocide, officials, and leaders who participated or incited others to participate, and those who committed rape and sexual torture. Category 2 included “notorious murderers,” those who tortured others or defiled their bodies, suspects who killed or intended to kill, and those who served as accom- plices in such acts. Finally, Category 3 was comprised of property offenders who had not yet come to settlement with victims or authorities before the law took effect. Courts were operational at both the cell (akagari) and sector (umurenge) levels of geographic administration. Those at the cell level (the smallest administrative region in Rwanda) were responsible for trying people who were accused of Category 3 by guest on September 21, 2014ccj.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://ccj.sagepub.com/ Nyseth Brehm et al. 337 crimes, while courts at the sector level were responsible for Categories 1 and 2.8 Nationwide, there were 9,013 cell courts, 1,545 sector courts, and 1,545 courts of appeal (National Service of Gacaca Jurisdictions, 2012). Each level of court consisted of a general assembly, a bench of judges (originally 19, later reduced to 14, 9, and finally 5), a president, and a coordinating committee. Lawyers did not participate in the trials, ostensibly to avoid adversarial proceedings, and there were no prosecutorial teams. Instead, the judges were tasked with investigating the crimes and then conduct- ing the trials, which lasted an average of 1 to 3 days (Mukantaganzwa, 2012). Trials took place in classrooms, conference rooms, or outdoors when indoor locations were not available. At each trial, inyangamugayo (judges) sat together on the bench, wearing green, yellow, and blue sashes—the colors of the Rwandan flag. The victims sat between the inyangamugayo and the public, with the perpetrators on the other side. Public confession was a cornerstone of the trials and their capacity to simultaneously serve the punitive and restorative goals of justice. As such, trials were open to the adult Rwandans in every community, whose participation was seen as key in moving the nation past the atrocity. In fact, participation was a duty (Organic Law n°16/2004, Article 29), and there are records of fines for non-participation (Sommers, 2012). The gacaca laws based punishments on the category of crime, recognition of guilt, and time to confession (if any). The most severe punishment that judges could assign was lifetime in prison. This was reserved for those committing Category 1 crimes without confession before or during the trials (Organic Law, 13/2008). Sentences were then to be decreased depending on the severity of the crime and time of confession (with lighter sentences for those who confessed before rather than during their trial). Community service, fines, and other restoration-based reparations were also possible sanctions, which we discuss in more detail below. Special procedures were put in place for minors. Rwandans who were between the ages of 14 and 18 at the time of the offense could be tried and receive up to 20 years in prison for a Category 1 crime. Those who were less than 14 at the time of the geno- cide were not to be prosecuted but sent to training camps instead (Organic Law, 13/2008). With regard to appeals, if defendants, victims, or others were not satisfied with a judgment, they were to register their intention to appeal within 15 days. The court then assessed the grounds of the appeals claim based on the gacaca laws. Assessing the Courts The courts closed on June 18, 2012, after completing the vast majority of the cases brought to their attention. To date, research on the gacaca courts has focused on schol- ars’ and practitioners’ assessments of the orientations and operations of the courts rather than case outcomes. Indeed, as the gacaca were heralded as a new form of transitional justice that uniquely combined mechanisms of punitive and restorative justice, diverse scholars sought to document how the courts functioned in law and in practice (Bornkamm, 2012; Clark, 2010; Daly, 2002; Longman, 2009; Schabas, 2005). In the course of this documentation, divergent views emerged regarding the pur- pose of the gacaca. For many practitioners and advocacy groups, the gacaca were by guest on September 21, 2014ccj.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://ccj.sagepub.com/ 338 Journal of Contemporary Criminal Justice 30(3) primarily a retributive-based institution that existed to punish perpetrators of geno- cide. Others, such as Karekezi (see, for example, Karekezi, Nshimiyimana, & Mutamba, 2004) and Drumbl (2000), argue that a view of the gacaca as strictly retrib- utive is inherently limiting. Rather, in combining punishment and reconciliation, the gacaca blend elements of retributive and restorative justice. Clark (2010) similarly views the gacaca’s goals as both punitive and restorative, though he moves beyond this binary distinction in proposing six ideal aims—truth, peace, justice, healing, for- giveness, and reconciliation—along with three more pragmatic objectives of process- ing the backlog of cases, improving living conditions in the prisons, and facilitating economic development. Beyond documenting the process and objectives of the gacaca, scholars have assessed Rwandan public opinion of the courts, with many finding generally favorable public sentiment (Gasibirege & Babalola, 2001; Longman, Pham, & Weinstein, 2004; Rettig, 2008).9 The courts have also sustained harsh criticism, however, as scholars and practitioners have critiqued the implementation of gacaca and the institution more generally (Apuuli, 2009; Fierens, 2005; Ingelaere, 2009; Rettig, 2008; Staub, 2004; Waldorf, 2006). These commentaries address a range of gacaca processes, including but not limited to the traumatic effects of testifying, the retroactive application of laws, the lack of due process rights for the accused, the reduced role of local communities in the creation of the courts, the inclusion of crimes against property, and the lack of trials against members of the RPF, the ruling party who assumed power after the genocide and who were accused of committing crimes in the process of stopping the genocide and in its immediate aftermath. Notably, the Rwandan government also echoes some of these concerns. In fact, the closing report of the National Service of Gacaca Jurisdictions listed many difficulties impeding the functioning of the courts, such as responding when gacaca judges and then-current government leaders were accused of genocide, conspiracy among both the accused and the witnesses to conceal informa- tion, destruction of court records, violence against those who testified, trauma mani- fested during (and likely after) court proceedings, accused perpetrators who fled Rwanda, and corruption within the court system. These critiques identify important problems, especially when measured against an idealized liberal legal model. When measured against the post-genocide Rwandan context, however, many of the legalistic critiques of the courts seem disproportionate, given the scale of crimes and the lack of other options to respond to them (McEvoy, 2007). Rwanda had just lost more than one million people to a genocide that its own citizens had planned and perpetrated, its institutions were completely shattered, and its pre-genocide legal system already differed from Western legal systems in numerous ways. With both context and critiques in mind, we here detail a form of justice the gacaca produced—the sanctions given to over one million perpetrators. Analytic Strategy To detail these sanctions, we draw on official records that were kept by the National Service of Gacaca Jurisdictions. This unit was the administrative arm of the gacaca by guest on September 21, 2014ccj.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://ccj.sagepub.com/ Nyseth Brehm et al. 339 courts, and they compiled records from all trials. Millions of these records were kept in official notebooks, which are currently being archived in Kigali. This process will take years, though gacaca employees also transferred abbreviated forms of court records into Excel files that contain information about the perpetrators (including sex, date of birth, and family identifiers), whether they were found guilty, the punishment, the category of crime, the location of the crime, and the date of the trial. Through a partnership with the Rwandan National Commission for the Fight Against Genocide, we obtained the Excel files for each administrative region within Rwanda. We then compiled these abbreviated court records from 10,558 courts10 into a single database of gacaca files with almost two million records. We caution that this is the first presen- tation of these data and it is likely that a small percentage of the almost two million cases in our Excel files contain clerical errors. Nevertheless, after taking care to clean these data and minimize such errors, we are confident about the data we present. In this article, we focus specifically on the initial sanctions imposed at the cell and sector levels. To avoid confusion and duplication, we omit appeals (explained in more detail below) from the analysis. In addition, we exclude trials in absence, which involved those who had fled or, for some other reason, did not appear in court 30 days after they were summoned. These trials were conducted not for the alleged perpetrator but for the victims, their families, and the community, illustrating the restorative aspect of the trials. Yet, as the sanctions were likely influenced by the inability of the accused to confess or testify on their own behalf, we exclude them from this analysis. We also exclude a relatively small percentage of cases that include errors. Official data in any country are never perfect, and Rwandan gacaca data are no exception. Therefore, while we strove to include as many cases as possible in this analysis, we exclude cases with errors, such as sanctions recorded incorrectly (with nonsensical numbers, words, or symbols). Thus, the total number of trials included in the analysis is 1,441,555. Note that the unit of analysis is the trial rather than the individual; a small proportion of individuals were tried for crimes in multiple categories and jurisdictions, whereas others were tried in separate cases for crimes falling into different categories. We begin by detailing the total number of cases concluded by the gacaca system. Then, we restrict the analysis to our analytic sample as described above and detail the sanctions received in each category of crime.11 Finally, we briefly examine how these sanctions varied by the age and sex of the perpetrators. The Gacaca Courts: An Overview Overall, the gacaca courts completed 1,958,634 cases (National Service of Gacaca Jurisdictions, 2012). Table 1 illustrates the case breakdown by category of genocidal crime, showing that, by far, the majority of the cases were crimes against property (Category 3). Thirty-three percent of the cases involved crimes against people, with 3% of all cases falling in Category 1, the category reserved for the cases deemed most seri- ous. Table 1 also includes the percentage of individuals found guilty in each category. The likelihood of a guilty verdict was highest for property crimes in Category 3 (96%), followed by those in Category 1 (88%). The high percentage of those convicted in by guest on September 21, 2014ccj.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://ccj.sagepub.com/ 340 Journal of Contemporary Criminal Justice 30(3) Category 3 may be explained in part by the relatively modest sanctions, as detailed below. In addition, the discrepancy between those convicted in Category 1 as opposed to Category 2 (63%) may be due in part to the percentage of confessions in each cate- gory (approximately 41% and 30%, respectively) or the notoriety of the perpetrators. Approximately 9% of the total cases tried by the gacaca were appeals cases. As the table illustrates, the vast majority of these cases were for crimes in Category 2, which included crimes against people, such as killing. Twenty-six percent (45,839) of all appeals cases were acquitted. As noted above, we exclude these cases, as well as cases tried in absentia and cases with erroneous data, resulting in an analytic database of 1,441,555 trials. Category 3 Sanctions: Crimes Against Property Table 2 shows the distribution of sanctions for Category 3 crimes—crimes against property—that were tried at the cell (akagari) level. The overwhelming majority of perpetrators in this category were sanctioned via fines that were to be paid to victims and their families. The median fine amount was 7,100 Rwandan Francs (RWF), which corresponds to approximately US$11 at the current exchange rates (649 RWF per U.S. dollar) and a relatively modest percentage of Rwanda’s per capita gross national income of US$560 (World Bank, 2013, data for 2011). Approximately half of the fines were between 1,285 and 25,000 RWF, or US$2 to US$39. As shown in Figure 1, almost one fourth of the fines were less than 1,000 RWF, and another third were below 10,000 RWF, likely reflecting the economic cir- cumstances of the perpetrators. At the other end of the distribution, 9% of fines exceeded 100,000 RWF, or US$154 (and 1% of fines exceeded 680,953 RWF, or US$1,049). The distribution is skewed by a small number of fines over 1,000,000 RWF, which may not have been accurately recorded. To assess the fine amount, the victim and/or family members would provide a list of the property that was destroyed. This list would be read aloud to the public during the hearing, and anyone present with additional information could provide it to the court. This was especially important when the entire family was killed; in such cases, the neighbors would generally assist the gacaca courts in assessing the damage to property and compiling the list. Then, if the suspects were found guilty of stealing or destroying the property in question, the gacaca court judges would decide how much was owed for the damaged or stolen property. The fines were intended to be paid to the Table 1. Gacaca Case Completion. Gacaca category Number of cases % Number found guilty % Appeals Category 1 60,552 3 53,426 88 19,177 Category 2 577,528 30 361,590 63 134,394 Category 3 1,320,554 67 1,266,632 96 25,170 Total 1,958,634 100 1,681,648 86 178,741 by guest on September 21, 2014ccj.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://ccj.sagepub.com/ Nyseth Brehm et al. 341 family rather than the state. If no family member survived the genocide, the fines were held in a special account at the district level, to be paid to any relatives who came forward at a later date. Beyond fines, over 9% of cases were settled by “agreement” (ubwumvikane). This represents a negotiated arrangement between the perpetrators and the victim or fami- lies who lost property, initiated by the perpetrator who wished to be forgiven and to pay the victim for the stolen or destroyed property. For example, an accused individual took four doors from a victim’s house during the genocide. By the time of the hearing, however, the accused had damaged the doors and could no longer find the same wood to replace them. If the accused recognized his crime and asked for forgiveness, he Table 2. Frequency Distribution of Category 3 Sanctions. Level 3 sanction Frequency % Finea 980,529 87.33 Agreement (Ubwumvikane) 104,289 9.29 Exemption (Gusonerwa) 25,593 2.28 Restitution/return goods 10,387 0.93 Forgiveness (Imbabazi) 698 0.06 Daily work 600 0.05 Building a house 554 0.05 Months in prisonb 117 0.01 Total 1,122,767 100.00 aPrecise fine amount information is missing for approximately 1% of the cases. bGacaca law stipulated that prison sentences were not to be given for Category 3 crimes. It is unclear whether the .01% of prison sentences in the database were errors in sentencing or errors in recording the sentence. Figure 1. Fines for Category 3 perpetrators (in Rwandan Francs). by guest on September 21, 2014ccj.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://ccj.sagepub.com/ 342 Journal of Contemporary Criminal Justice 30(3) could ask the victim for an agreement. Together, the two parties would then choose another wood to replace the damaged doors. Once chosen, their agreement would then be signed before the gacaca court, with the court retaining the ultimate authority to accept or reject the agreement. In addition, over 25,000 cases (2.3%) were resolved via gusonerwa or “exemption.” In such cases, both perpetrator(s) and victim(s) recognized the crime. The perpetrator requested exemption from all or part of the financial obligation, and the victim decided whether to grant this request. If the victim agreed, the perpetrator’s crimes would still be recognized as such, though no fine or other punishment would be assigned. For example, an individual was accused of looting two cows from a victim’s family. During the trial, he was found guilty and sentenced to pay 80,000 RWF to the victim’s family. He sold many of his belongings to try to come up with 80,000 RWF. After a few months, he visited the victim’s family. He brought 60,000 RWF—the most he could get at that time—and promised to bring the remaining money soon. After consultation, the family decided to forgive him and exempted him from paying the remaining 20,000 RWF. Beyond this, about 1% of Category 3 cases were resolved through the return of goods. These included cows, pigs, sheep, metal sheets, clothing, glasses, basins, knives, coffee, beans, peas, pitchers, blankets, saucepans, and other animals, foods, and household goods. The remaining sanction categories listed were imposed less fre- quently but remain important for understanding the variety of approaches to restor- ative justice for crimes against property. For example, perpetrators could request “forgiveness” (imbabazi) for their crimes. This did not deny the crime’s occurrence or the suspect’s participation, since recognizing the crime is an important part of the gacaca process. Forgiveness was also an element of other sanction processes, such as exemption or agreement. Yet, when officially granted, the victim agreed not to pursue the perpetrator for damages. Finally, some of those found guilty were given the option to build a house or work for the victims. This served as a form of restitution and rec- onciliation, particularly in cases in which the guilty party lacked the means to pay fines or repay stolen goods. Category 1 and Category 2 Sanctions: Crimes Against People Cases involving crimes against people, such as killing, rape, and torture, were addressed through courts at the sector (umurenge) level, a higher administrative level within Rwanda. Nevertheless, they were designed to operate according to similar procedures and were governed by the same laws. Due to the greater severity of these crimes, the sentences for these categories were much more likely to involve incarceration. In fact, almost all of the Category 1 and Category 2 perpetrators were given prison sentences, as shown in Table 3. Approximately 93% received a sentence varying from several months to 30 years. In addition, 5% received a life sentence.12 There were also 329 agreements recorded in the data, which functioned as explained above for prop- erty offenses, and 100 sentences to training camps, where those sentenced took classes in Rwandan history and learned skills pertaining to agriculture, woodwork, and art, among others. by guest on September 21, 2014ccj.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://ccj.sagepub.com/ Nyseth Brehm et al. 343 Community service, a hallmark of the gacaca system and restorative justice more generally, remained an option for perpetrators in these categories who confessed to their crimes. Overall, 29% of cases (91,556 cases) involved a community service obli- gation. When perpetrators recognized their crimes and confessed, the sentence length could be halved through community service, with 50% of the sentenced time served in TIG (Travaux d’Interet General or “works of public interest”) rather than prison. Community service work generally depended on the needs of the region, often includ- ing tasks such as building (or rebuilding) homes for survivors, repairing roads and bridges, planting fauna, or creating terraces. This work was completed prior to the prison sentence. Figure 2 shows the distribution of sentence length for these two types of genocide offenses.13 Category 1 crimes are considered significantly more serious than Category 2 offenses, meriting longer prison sentences. The modal Category 1 sentence was 25 to 30 years, with 17% of the perpetrators receiving life sentences. Excluding the life sentences, the median sentence length was 19 years—or a year less than the presump- tive minimum of 20 years. In Category 2, by contrast, the median sentence was 15 years, the modal interval was 10 to 14 years, and only 2% received life sentences. Table 3. Frequency Distribution of Category 1 and Category 2 Sanctions. Level 1 and 2 sanctions Frequency % Prison sentence 296,245 92.93 With community service 91,556 Without community service 204,689 Life in prison 15,444 4.85 Fines 6,670 2.09 Agreements 329 0.10 Training camp 100 0.03 Total 318,788 100.00 Figure 2. Prison sentences for Category 1 and Category 2 perpetrators. by guest on September 21, 2014ccj.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://ccj.sagepub.com/ 344 Journal of Contemporary Criminal Justice 30(3) Figure 3. Sentences and community service for Category 1 and Category 2 perpetrators. These distributions thus show a degree of proportionality in sentencing across this severity gradient. As a point of reference, 23% of U.S. homicide offenders were given life sentences in 2006. The remainder were sentenced for an average of 21 years (Rosenmerkel, Durose, & Farole, 2009, p. 6), significantly longer than sentences given to genocide perpetrators tried in the gacaca courts. While the United States remains an outlier in regard to sentence length, the sparing use of life sentences for gacaca Category 2 crimes also appears tough but fair by international standards (Bernaz, 2013). Figure 3 shows the distribution of sentence length in years for Category 1 and Category 2 crimes combined, as well as the number within each 5-year grouping that received community service. Notably, the most common prison sentences were 10 to 14 years in length, though more than one third of the individuals receiving these sen- tences were able to lessen their time in prison by doing community service. In addi- tion, some prisoners were eligible to have up to one third of their sentence suspended.14 Age and Sex Distribution of Sentences We have only limited information about the demographic and social characteristics of perpetrators, but it is instructive to compare the sex and age distributions of those receiving punishments (for more information on the age and sex of perpetrators, see by guest on September 21, 2014ccj.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://ccj.sagepub.com/ Nyseth Brehm et al. 345 (Nyseth Brehm, Uggen, & Gasanabo, 2012).15 In general, a greater percentage of men received fines for Category 3 crimes, with a median fine amount of 7,480 RWF for men and 5,000 RWF for women. Yet, for Categories 1 and 2, the median length of years in prison (15) was the same for men and women, and community service was given in a similar percentage of cases. With regard to age at the time of offense, the average fine was 8,155 RWF for people at or below the median age of 32, relative to 7,435 RWF for people 33 and above. In addition, the median length of prison sen- tences was 12 years for those less than age 33 and 13 years for those over age 33 and above. Figure 4 shows life sentences by age and sex. As discussed, life sentences were the most severe punishments given by the courts. Overall, 17% of men convicted of Category 1 crimes were given life sentences, relative to 7% of women in this category. In Category 2, men are also more likely to receive life sentences, which again could reflect differences in severity or other characteristics of the case or the court. About 16% of perpetrators below the median age of 32 received life sentences for Category 1 crimes, relative to 11% of their older counterparts. There is little difference in the age distribution of life sentences for Category 2 crimes. Overall, these differences are small, with more difference seen between sexes and in Category 3 crimes. As there are no similar studies of sanctions for perpetrators of other episodes of genocide, we are unable to compare these discrepancies with other cases. Moreover, we lack the sort of detailed information about crime severity that would allow us to analyze discrimination on the basis of sex and age. Nevertheless, age and sex are likely linked to both crime severity and sentencing outcomes (Steffensmeier, Ulmer, & Kramer, 1998). Discrepancies in fines may also reflect differences in the abil- ity to pay financial obligations. Finally, there may have been gender- or age-specific differences in confessions (which, again, influenced the sanctions given) or differences Figure 4. Life sentences by age and sex. Note. Ninety-eight percent of all life sentences were given to men, whereas 61% of life sentences were given to people who were at or below the median age of 32 when they committed the crime. by guest on September 21, 2014ccj.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://ccj.sagepub.com/ 346 Journal of Contemporary Criminal Justice 30(3) in sentence assignment by the judges. As more complete gacaca data become available, a full accounting of the relative influence of such factors may be undertaken. Conclusion: Gacaca in Perspective In the past decade, the National Service of Gacaca Jurisdictions processed an astounding number of cases in an attempt to bring perpetrators of genocide to justice and to promote reconciliation within Rwanda. This system represents a complex amalgamation of seem- ingly disparate elements. It is at once formal and informal, community-based and state- driven, traditional and contemporary, and punitive and restorative. The underlying tensions within the gacaca model, combined with the enormity of the courts’ responsi- bilities, have led to sustained criticism with regard to both process and outcomes (Apuuli, 2009; Fierens, 2005; Ingelaere, 2009; Rettig, 2008; Staub, 2004; Waldorf, 2006). We do not seek to refute these criticisms. Nevertheless, the courts’ ability to try and sanction a crushing caseload of genocide perpetrators represents a truly historic achievement in the administration of justice. Whereas one cannot measure the quality of justice by the number of cases processed, it is important to reiterate that the gacaca courts did their difficult work in the wake of a mass tragedy that shattered Rwanda’s legal infrastructure and left the country reeling. To put these accomplishments in perspective, consider that the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda has com- pleted 75 cases since 1997, with annual budgets over US$200 million (ICTR, 2013a). In contrast, the gacaca processed almost two million cases at an estimated total cost of US$46 to US$65 million (National Service of Gacaca Jurisdictions, 2012). While punishment was not the only purpose or outcome of the courts, it is clearly an important aspect of the institution that merits scholarly attention and analysis. This article provides the first comprehensive overview of the sanctions given by the gacaca courts and the first attempt to organize and analyze these data. Although much work remains, we can draw three basic conclusions from the data presented here. First, the sanctions of the gacaca courts reflect a mix of fines and restorative justice alternatives for genocide offenses against property, illustrating that restorative aims were indeed embedded in the institution. Second, the severity-graded prison sentences for genocide crimes against people provide evidence of proportionality and a more punitive approach toward crimes deemed more serious. While it is difficult to charac- terize any genocide sanction as proportional, the sentences appear to reflect the sever- ity gradient intended by the basic categorization scheme. It is perhaps noteworthy that, on average, sentences for murder and non-negligent manslaughter in the United States are significantly longer. Third, while the gacaca courts made extensive use of life sentences and long-term imprisonment, they also made extensive use of community service (Travaux d’Interet General or “works of public interest”). Further research on these restorative efforts might explore their potential to serve tremendously disadvan- taged communities while also alleviating prison overcrowding, costs, and a severely overtaxed prison infrastructure. In short, the gacaca courts represented a powerful response to mass crime and an important element in the struggle to address society-wide tragedy and move forward. by guest on September 21, 2014ccj.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://ccj.sagepub.com/ Nyseth Brehm et al. 347 While these courts represent a “home-grown” Rwandan solution in many ways, their blending of punitive and restorative aims and traditional and contemporary elements holds important insights for justice pursuits around the world. To the extent that a hybrid model such as gacaca can address the “crime of crimes,” it should encourage other innovative approaches to lesser offenses in wide-ranging social contexts. Appendix Abbreviated Gacaca Categories Category 1: 1. Any person who committed or was an accomplice in the commission of an offense that puts him or her in the category of planners or organizers of the genocide or crimes against humanity; 2. Any person who was at a national leadership level or that of prefecture (state) level— including those serving in public administration, political parties, army, gendarmerie, religious denominations, or a militia—who committed crimes of genocide or crimes against humanity or encouraged others to partici- pate in such crimes, together with his or her accomplice; 3. Any person who committed or was an accomplice in the commission of offense that puts him or her among the category of people who incited, supervised, and were ringleaders of genocide or crimes against humanity; 4. Any person who was at the leadership level at the sub-prefecture and com- mune (municipality)— including those serving in public administration, politi- cal parties, army, gendarmerie, communal police, religious denominations, or a militia—who committed any crimes of genocide or other crimes against humanity or encouraged others to commit similar offenses, together with his or her accomplice; and 5. Any person who committed the offense of rape or sexual torture, together with his or her accomplice. Category 2: 1. A notorious murderer who distinguished himself or herself in his or her loca- tion or wherever he or she passed due to the zeal and cruelty used, together with his or her accomplice; 2. Any person who tortured another even though such torture did not result into death, together with his or her accomplice; 3. Any person who committed a dehumanizing act on a dead body, together with his or her accomplice; 4. Any person who committed or was an accomplice in the commission of an offense that puts him or her on the list of people who killed or attacked others resulting in death, together with his or her accomplice; by guest on September 21, 2014ccj.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://ccj.sagepub.com/ 348 Journal of Contemporary Criminal Justice 30(3) 5. Any person who injured or attacked another with the intention to kill but such intention was not fulfilled, together with his or her accomplice; and 6. Any person who committed or aided another to commit an offense against another without an intention to kill, together with his or her accomplice. Category 3: A person who only committed an offense related to property. However, when the offender and the victim came to a settlement and settled the matter before authorities or witnesses before commencement of the law, the offender was not prosecuted. Acknowledgment We owe special thanks to Marie Berry, Suzy McElrath, Naphtal Kisakye, Lindsay Blahnik, and Andrew Johnson for valuable feedback. Declaration of Conflicting Interests The author(s) declared no potential conflicts of interest with respect to the research, authorship, and/or publication of this article. Funding The author(s) disclosed receipt of the following financial support for the research, authorship, and/or publication of this article: This research was supported by the University of Minnesota Graduate Research Partnership Program. Uggen is additionally supported by a Robert Wood Johnson Health Investigator Award, whereas Nyseth Brehm is supported by the National Science Foundation. Notes 1. The population is based on the 1991 census, the last census before the genocide. Thus, this is an approximation. 2. The term “genocide” was not common during the 1940s. Instead, the Tribunal had jurisdic- tion over war crimes, crimes against humanity, crimes against peace, and conspiracy. 3. Truth commissions gained prominence as a potential response to mass atrocities during the 1970s (Avruch & Vejarano, 2001; Minow, 2008). Unlike punitive responses that empha- size retribution, general deterrence, and “just desserts,” commissions place more emphasis on creating a record of events that occurred during a period of violence, often offering amnesty or reduced sentences in exchange for truth telling. 4. The outcomes of these trials are not well documented. However, a small percentage of those in prison were executed. The last executions took place in 1998, when 22 people found guilty of genocide-related crimes were executed (Amnesty International, 2007). Later, exe- cutions reportedly stopped, and the death penalty was officially abolished in 2007. 5. As detailed by the Government, the gacaca courts had five key objectives, including the following: (a) identifying the truth about what happened during the genocide, (b) increasing the speed of ongoing trials, (c) fighting a culture of impunity, (d) contributing to the national unity and reconciliation process, and (e) demonstrating the capacity of the Rwandan people to resolve their problems (National Service of Gacaca Jurisdictions, 2012). by guest on September 21, 2014ccj.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://ccj.sagepub.com/ Nyseth Brehm et al. 349 6. Whereas the vast majority of genocidal violence took place between April and July, 1994, the jurisdiction spanned a longer period to try people involved in planning the genocide as well as those involved in attacks after the genocide was declared over in July 1994. 7. Judgments were not given during the pilot phase, though information collected during this phase was used during future court proceedings. Throughout the pilot phases, Rwandan leaders adapted the laws governing the gacaca courts based on practice (Brannigan & Jones, 2009). In total, the laws governing the gacaca courts were amended several times, though court procedures remained relatively stable. Relevant laws are listed in the works cited (Organic Law n°40/2000; Organic Law n°16/2004; Organic Law n°28/2006; Organic Law n°13/2008; n°10/2007; n°04/2012). 8. Until 2008, the gacaca courts only had jurisdiction over Categories 2 and 3, while Category 1 suspects were sent to the national courts. The 2008 modifications to the laws shifted many Category 1 suspects to the gacaca, however. Data on suspects tried within the national courts are currently unavailable. 9. In line with this, the Center for Conflict Management of the National University of Rwanda (2012) conducted a survey of approximately 3,500 people to assess public opinion of the courts, finding that 87% of respondents believed the gacaca strengthened national unity and reconciliation and put an end to the culture of impunity. However, some have noted that these and other surveys are “suspiciously positive,” which might be attributed to fear of criticizing the government and its initiatives (e.g., Rettig, 2008). 10. As noted below, this number is lower than the total number of courts because we exclude courts of appeal from this analysis. 11. Ideally, we would be able to analyze punishments by type of crime, such as rape or torture. However, crimes in the database are only listed by category, so we do not have the capabil- ity to disaggregate our data beyond the three categories. 12. There were also 10 cases in which sentences over 30 years are recorded, although the maximum sentence length was limited to 30 years or life imprisonment by statute. These 10 cases have no perceptible effect on the mean or median values reported here. 13. For those who were convicted of crimes in more than one court, prison sentences were allowed to be served concurrently rather than consecutively. 14. There was also a mass amnesty in 2003, though details about these amnesties are not publi- cally available. 15. Age information is missing for approximately 30% of cases; sex information is missing for 0.1% of cases. References Amnesty International. (2007, August 2). Rwanda abolishes death penalty. Retrieved from http://www.amnesty.org/en/news-and-updates/good-news/rwanda-abolishes-death- penalty-20070802 Apuuli, K. P. (2009). Procedural due process and the prosecution of genocide suspects in Rwanda. Journal of Genocide Research, 11, 11-30. Avruch, K., & Vejarano, B. (2001). Truth and reconciliation commissions: A review essay and anno- tated bibliography. Social Justice: Anthropology, Peace, and Human Rights, 2(1-2), 47-108. Bass, G. (2000). Stay the hand of vengeance: The politics of war crimes tribunals. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Bernaz, N. (2013). Life imprisonment and the prohibition of inhuman punishments in interna- tional human rights law: Moving the agenda forward. Human Rights Quarterly, 35, 470-497. by guest on September 21, 2014ccj.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://www.amnesty.org/en/news-and-updates/good-news/rwanda-abolishes-death-penalty-20070802 http://www.amnesty.org/en/news-and-updates/good-news/rwanda-abolishes-death-penalty-20070802 http://ccj.sagepub.com/ 350 Journal of Contemporary Criminal Justice 30(3) Bornkamm, P. C. (2012). Rwanda’s Gacaca courts: Between retribution and reparation. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. Brannigan, A., & Jones, N. A. (2009). Genocide and the legal process in Rwanda from genocide amnesty to the new rule of law. International Criminal Justice Review, 19, 192-207. Center for Conflict Management of the National University of Rwanda. (2012). Evaluation of gacaca process: Achieved results per objective. Study commissioned by National Service of Gacaca Courts. Kigali, Rwanda. Clark, P. (2010). The Gacaca courts, post-genocide justice and reconciliation in Rwanda: Justice without lawyers. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. Daly, E. (2002). Between punitive and reconstructive justice: The Gacaca courts in Rwanda. New York University Journal of International Law and Politics, 34, 355-396. Drumbl, M. A. (2000). Punishment, postgenocide: From guilt to shame to “civis” in Rwanda. New York University Law Review, 75, 1221-1326. Drumbl, M. A. (2002). Restorative justice and collective responsibility: Lessons for and from the Rwandan genocide. Contemporary Justice Review, 5, 5-22. Fierens, J. (2005). Gacaca courts: Between fantasy and reality. Journal of International Criminal Justice, 3, 896-919. Fujii, L. (2009). Killing neighbors: Webs of violence in Rwanda. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Gacaca Report Summary. (2012). Summary of the report presented at the closing of Gacaca court activities. National Service of Gacaca Jurisdictions. Kigali, Rwanda. Gasibirege, S., & Babalola, S. (2001). Perceptions about the Gacaca law in Rwanda: Evidence from a multi-method study, special publication no. 19. Baltimore, MD: Center for Communication Programs, School of Public Health, Johns Hopkins University. Hatzfeld, J. (2008). A time for machetes: The Rwandan genocide—The killers speak (L. Coverdale, Trans.). London, England: Sperpent’s Tail. Heberer, P., & Matthaus, J. (2008). Atrocities on trial: Historical perspectives on the politics of prosecuting war crimes. Lincoln, Nebraska: University of Nebraska Press. Ingelaere, B. (2009). Does the truth pass across the fire without burning? Locating the short circuit in Rwanda’s Gacaca courts. The Journal of Modern African Studies, 47, 507-528. International Center for Prison Studies. (2013). World prison statistics archive. Retrieved from http://www.prisonstudies.org/country/rwanda International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda. (2013a). Annual budget. Retrieved from http:// www.unictr.org/Abouta/GeneralInformation/tabid/101/Default.aspx International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda. (2013b). Status of cases. Retrieved from http:// www.unictr.org/Cases/StatusofCases/tabid/204/Default.aspx Jones, N. (2009). The courts of genocide: Politics and the rule of law in Rwanda and Arusha. New York, NY: Routledge. Karekezi, A. U., Nshimiyimana, A., & Mutamba, B. (2004). Localizing justice: Gacaca courts in post-genocide Rwanda. In E. Stover & H. M. Weinstein (Eds.), My neighbor, my enemy: Justice and community in the aftermath of mass atrocity (pp. 69-84). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. Longman, T. (2009). An assessment of Rwanda’s Gacaca courts. Peace Review, 21, 304-312. Longman, T., Pham, P., & Weinstein, H. (2004). Connecting justice to human experience. In E. Stover & H. M. Weinstein (Eds.), My neighbor, my enemy: Justice and community in the aftermath of mass atrocity (pp. 206-225). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. Mamdani, M. (2001). When victims become killers: Colonialism, nativism, and genocide in Rwanda. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. by guest on September 21, 2014ccj.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://www.prisonstudies.org/country/rwanda http://www.unictr.org/Abouta/GeneralInformation/tabid/101/Default.aspx http://www.unictr.org/Abouta/GeneralInformation/tabid/101/Default.aspx http://www.unictr.org/Cases/StatusofCases/tabid/204/Default.aspx http://www.unictr.org/Cases/StatusofCases/tabid/204/Default.aspx http://ccj.sagepub.com/ Nyseth Brehm et al. 351 McEvoy, K. (2007). Beyond legalism: Towards a thicker understanding of transitional justice. Journal of Law and Society, 34, 411-440. Minow, M. (2008). Making history or making peace: When prosecutions should give way to truth commissions and peace negotiations. Journal of Human Rights, 7, 175-185. Mukantaganzwa, D. (2012). Interview with the executive secretary of National Gacaca Service Domithile Mukantaganzwa on the eve of closing of Gacaca courts. Retrieved from http:// www.gov.rw/Interview-with-the-Executive-Secretary-of-National-Gacaca-Service- Domithile-Mukantaganzwa-at-the-eve-of-closing-of-Gacaca-Courts Nyseth Brehm, H. N., Uggen, C., & Gasanabo, J.-D. (2012, November). Age, sex, and the crime of genocide. Paper presented at the 2012 meetings of the American Society of Criminology. Chicago, IL. Rettig, M. (2008). Gacaca: Truth, justice, and reconciliation in postconflict Rwanda? African Studies Review, 51(3), 25-50. Rosenmerkel, S., Durose, M., & Farole, D., Jr. (2009). Felony sentences in state courts, 2006— Statistical tables (U.S. Department of Justice, Bureau of Justice Statistics). Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office. Schabas, W. A. (2005). Genocide trials and Gacaca courts. Journal of International Criminal Justice, 3, 879-895. Sommers, M. (2012). Stuck: Rwandan youth and the struggle for adulthood. Athens: University of Georgia Press. Staub, E. (2004). Justice, healing, and reconciliation: How the people’s courts in Rwanda can promote them. Peace and Conflict: Journal of Peace Psychology, 10, 25-32. Steffensmeier, D., Ulmer, J., & Kramer, J. (1998). The interaction of race, gender, and age in criminal sentencing: The punishment cost of being young, black, and male. Criminology, 36, 763-797. Straus, S. (2006). The order of genocide: Race, power, and war in Rwanda. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Vandeginste, S. (1999, November 8-12). Justice, genocide, and reparation after genocide and crimes against humanity: The proposed establishment of population Gacaca tri- bunals in Rwanda. Paper delivered to the All-Africa Conference on African Principles of Conflict Resolution and Reconciliation, United Nations Conference Center, Addis Ababa, Ethiopia. Waldorf, L. (2006). Rwanda’s railing experiment in restorative justice. In D. Sullivan & L. Tifft (Eds.), Handbook of restorative justice: A global perspective (pp. 422-434). New York, NY: Routledge. World Bank. (2013). World Bank development indicators, 1960-2012. Retrieved from http:// data.worldbank.org/data-catalog/world-development-indicators/wdi-2011 Gacaca Laws Organic Law n°04/2012 of 15/06/2012 terminating Gacaca courts. Government of Rwanda. Organic Law n°10/2007 of 01/03/2007 amending Organic Law of 2004. Government of Rwanda. Organic Law n°13/2008 of 19/05/2008 amending previous Organic Laws. Government of Rwanda. Organic Law n°28/2006 of 27/06/2006 setting up the first amendment of Organic Law of 2004. Government of Rwanda. Organic Law n°16/2004 of 19/06/2004 governing the organization, jurisdiction, and functioning of Gacaca courts. Government of Rwanda. by guest on September 21, 2014ccj.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://www.gov.rw/Interview-with-the-Executive-Secretary-of-National-Gacaca-Service-Domithile-Mukantaganzwa-at-the-eve-of-closing-of-Gacaca-Courts http://www.gov.rw/Interview-with-the-Executive-Secretary-of-National-Gacaca-Service-Domithile-Mukantaganzwa-at-the-eve-of-closing-of-Gacaca-Courts http://www.gov.rw/Interview-with-the-Executive-Secretary-of-National-Gacaca-Service-Domithile-Mukantaganzwa-at-the-eve-of-closing-of-Gacaca-Courts http://data.worldbank.org/data-catalog/world-development-indicators/wdi-2011 http://data.worldbank.org/data-catalog/world-development-indicators/wdi-2011 http://ccj.sagepub.com/ 352 Journal of Contemporary Criminal Justice 30(3) Organic Law n°40/2000 of 26/01/2001governing the creation of Gacaca courts. Government of Rwanda. Author Biographies Hollie Nyseth Brehm is an Assistant Professor of Sociology at The Ohio State University. She studies genocide, crime, law, and transitional justice. Christopher Uggen is a Distinguished McKnight Professor of Sociology and Law at the University of Minnesota. He studies crime, law, and deviance, firm in the belief that good sci- ence can light the way to a more just and peaceful world. Jean-Damascène Gasanabo has a PhD in Education from the University of Geneva, Switzerland. He is currently Director General in charge of the Research and Documentation Center on Genocide within the Rwanda National Commission for the Fight against Genocide. by guest on September 21, 2014ccj.sagepub.comDownloaded from http://ccj.sagepub.com/ work_jd6x2xgehndfdddmth2rllwr7q ---- Justice and the spatial imagination HAL Id: hal-01258169 https://hal-enpc.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01258169 Submitted on 18 Jan 2016 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- entific research documents, whether they are pub- lished or not. The documents may come from teaching and research institutions in France or abroad, or from public or private research centers. L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires publics ou privés. Justice and the spatial imagination Mustafa Dikec To cite this version: Mustafa Dikec. Justice and the spatial imagination. Environment and Planning, 2001, �10.1068/a3467�. �hal-01258169� https://hal-enpc.archives-ouvertes.fr/hal-01258169 https://hal.archives-ouvertes.fr Introduction In an article published almost two decades ago, G H Pirie (1983, page 472) wrote: `̀ It would be a pity indeed if the busyness of political philosophers was to go completely unnoticed by spatial theorists and applied researchers. Equally, it would be a pity ... if this essay were to stand alone as a review of implications of that busyness.'' In that article, entitled `̀ On spatial justice'', Pirie reflected `̀ on the desirability and possibility of fashioning a concept of spatial justice from notions of social justice and territorial social justice'' (page 465). The present paper offers yet another reflection on the notion of justice as it relates to space and spatiality, to point to the ways in which various forms of injustice are manifest in the very process of spatialization, and the ways in which an increased awareness of the dialectical relationship between (in)justice and spatiality could make space a site of politics in fighting against injustice. As will become clear further through the text, the conceptualizations of both justice and space differ from the ways Pirie once viewed them. The paper is organized in five sections. The first section is a brief review of the geography literature which engages with the notion of justice, and serves to outline the theoretical position assumed in this paper. The second section provides an urban context in which a notion of spatial justice may be conceptualized. The third section is devoted to such a conceptualization. The fourth section presents the case of French urban policy in order to make the arguments more concrete. The concluding section is an attempt to define an ethico-political ground on which emancipatory politics in an urban spatial framework may be defended. The paper is conceptual in nature. Examples, however, are provided to stir the imagination as to the ways in which the dialectical relationship between (in)justice and spatiality may be conceived. The examples, there- fore, are used to make this relationship more concrete, rather than attempting to provide a thorough discussion of the cases selected. Justice and the spatial imagination Mustafa Dikec° Department of Urban Planning, University of California Los Angeles, 3250 Public Policy Building, Los Angeles, CA 90095-1656, USA; e-mail: mdikec@yahoo.com Received 13 March 2001; in revised form 9 July 2001 Environment and Planning A 2001, volume 33, pages 1785 ^ 1805 Abstract. I attempt in this paper to conceptualize a notion of spatial justice in order to point to the dialectical relationship between (in)justice and spatiality, and to the role that spatialization plays in the production and reproduction of domination and repression. I argue that the city provides a productive ground for the formation of a spatially informed ethics of political solidarity against domination and repression. A `triad' is articulated to inform such politics, which brings together three notions: the spatial dialectics of injustice, the right to the city, and the right to difference. The notion of spatial justice is employed as a theoretical underpinning to avoid abusive interpretations of Lefebvrian rights in a liberal framework of individual rights. The case of French urban policy is used for illustrative purposes. Finally, the notion of ëgalibertë is introduced as a moral ground on which the triad may be defended. DOI:10.1068/a3467 mailto:mdikec@yahoo.com Geographical encounters(1) `̀ The explicit engagement of geography with morality and social justice'', David Smith (1994, page 4) argues, `̀ dates from the latter part of the 1960s''. There is, of course, good reason to believe this. The movements of the 1960s and 1970s brought to attention issues, such as identity politics, rights to the city, rights to difference, and social justice, to name a few, and have been influential in almost every discipline. Geography was no exception. The first explicit attempt to link justice to geographical terms was made by Bleddyn Davies, who first coined the term `territorial justice' in his 1968 book entitled Social Needs and Resources in Local Services. Davies's conceptualization was norma- tive in nature, designed to assess the distribution of local services with respect to the needs of designated service areas. Approaches of this kind came under close scrutiny with the emergence of the so-called radical geography of the early 1970s. Regional science methods were criticized as being dehumanizing and distracting attention from social problems, and attention, accordingly, `̀ moved on to the processes responsible for spatial disparities in people's life chances: for what was beginning to be recognized as spatial injustice'' (Smith, 1994, page 5). The book that broke new ground came out in 1973. David Harvey, in his Social Justice and the City, sought to push John Rawls's (1971) liberal formulations to its limits, with a territorial twist, and arrived at a notion of `territorial social justice', which he defined as `̀ a just distribution justly arrived at''. Harvey, however, was more interested in the structural dynamics of the capitalist society, and therefore, not merely in distribution but, above all, in issues of production. Rawls's scheme, which did not have production at its core and which, indeed, left it to the workings of the market, would not take him there. Davies's initial conceptualization and Harvey's earlier work have been influential in stimulating research on the spatiality of social justice, and the notion of territorial justice still guides research (see, for example, Boyne and Powell, 1991). A shift in focus occurred with the publication of Iris Marion Young's Justice and the Politics of Differ- ence (1990). Harvey (1992) engaged again with the notion of justice, this time building not on Rawls, but on Young, with an emphasis on forms of oppression as sources of injustice. This was followed, with a diminished interest in Young's formulation, by a modification of his earlier formulation as `̀ just production of just geographical differ- ence''. His central concerns now were uneven geographical development as an intrinsic feature of the capitalist mode of production, and the social construction of principles of justice (Harvey, 1996). Although Young's work was initially embraced, it was later criticized for its `difference'-guided identity politics by scholars seeking strategic forms of essentialism, such as human sameness, as sources of ethico-political solidarity (Smith, 1997; 2000). To recapitulate: geography's engagement with social justice started with an exclu- sive concern on distribution in a Cartesian space (Davies, 1968); continued with an emphasis on production, the workings of the capitalist city, and uneven geographies of capitalism (Harvey, 1973; 1996); shifted focus with a celebration of identity and differ- ence, and an emphasis not on justice and consensus, but on injustice and dissensus (Gleeson, 1998; Harvey, 1992; Merrifield, 1997; Merrifield and Swyngedouw, 1997); and ended up, for the moment, with a problematization of the preoccupation with difference, and a search for universal bonds of solidarity (Smith, 1997; 2000). There have been few studies, however, that have explicitly employed a notion of `spatial justice'. One of these was Steven Flusty's (1994) study of the built environment (1) This section is a condensed version of Dikec° (2001). A recently published review may also be found in Smith (2000). 1786 M Dikec° in Los Angeles, where he argued for an equitable distribution of spatial resources for all to ensure spatial justice given that space is claimed by dominant groups in the society. This, of course, is a most welcome and challenging statement but Flusty, rather than elaborating the notion, focused merely on form to the neglect of the structural dynamics of the particular kind of spatialization that he wanted to analyze. The most recent engagement with the spatial dimension of justice, by explicitly employing the term spatial justice, has been that of Edward Soja (2000) in his Postmetropolis, as part of his ongoing project for the assertion of the spatiality of human life and the formation of spatially conscious politics initiated in his earlier work (1989). The article that opens this paper was an explicit attempt to conceptualize a notion of spatial justice. Pirie's spatial sensibilities were certainly intriguing. However, his conceptualization deserved a reservation. He, admittedly, treated space `̀ in the [then]- familiar way as some kind of container, as an entity or physical expression made up of individual locations and their distance relations'' (1983, page 471). It is a pity that Pirie stopped at what seems to be a perfect starting point (1983, pages 471, 472; emphasis added): `̀ This notion of space is not inviolate. It may also be conceived of as a social creationöas a structure created by society and not merely as a context for society ... . Conceptualizing spatial justice in terms of a view of space as process, and perhaps in terms of radical notions of justice, stands as an exacting challenge and, not unlikely, as the single occasion there might be for requiring and constructuring a concept of spatial justice. ... In spite of the challenge of spatial fetishism, and in spite of the radical assault on liberal distributive concerns, it would be worthwhile investigating the possibility of matching justice to notions of socially constructed space.'' What follows, then, is an endeavour that undertakes this enticing suggestion. Before moving on to the next section, I return briefly to Rawls, and chart some of the criticisms levelled against his work for they provide the agenda around which the present paper is structured. A recurring critique directed against Rawls was his con- viction of a single conception of justice that can rationally be defined, presupposing a rather homogeneous public with no serious conflicts. Later, in his Political Liberalism, Rawls (1993) modified his previous `well-ordered' view of society, recognized conflicts with a postulate of consensus, and admitted that his conception of society as relatively homogeneous in his earlier work was no longer a plausible assumption. His postulate of consensus, however, was not without problems. He was still inclined `̀ to keep incommensurability outside the public realm and admit to it only when reasonable and capable of contributing to his overlapping consensus'' (Katznelson, 1997, page 52). The recognition of this problem guided The Urbanization of Injustice (Merrifield and Swyngedouw, 1997) which was a collection of essays attempting to reconsider the lessons learned from Harvey's Social Justice and the City (1973), in the light of debates around `difference' and `nontotalizing' discourses. The focus, therefore, was not on consensus, but on dissensus and injustice. The conceptual tool for such an approach was provided by Young, according to whom injustice `̀ should be defined primarily in terms of the concepts of oppression and domination, rather than distribution'' (1990, page 192). Although `̀ Young's alternative vision for justice remains inchoate, she certainly provides a powerful theory of injustice''' (Gleeson, 1998, page 89), and the framework she provides seems to be a productive terrain on which to construe a notion of spatial justice, for spatialization (the mode of social production of space) is one of the major systematic producers of domination and oppression: that is, of injustice. Some of the basic tenets of this project may now be discerned. The argument is built around the social production of space, with the idea that the very production Justice and the spatial imagination 1787 of space, which is inherently a conflictual process, not only manifests various forms of injustice, but actually produces and reproduces them (thereby maintaining established social relations of domination and oppression). Such an approach clearly departs from an exclusively distributional approach. This, however, does not negate the importance of distributional issues, since, for example, `̀ when people are utterly excluded from active political participation in city affairs, distributional issues, of the sorts Rawls pinpoints, are often all that is left for communities and groups to organize around and to seek substantive representation'' (Merrifield, 1997, page 202). What should be criticized in the distributive paradigm, therefore, is the tendency to reduce social justice to distribution. I try to reconcile this tension through a notion of spatial dialectics of injustice, in an attempt neither to overvalorize nor to devalorize distributional matters. The attempt here, it should be noted, is not one aimed at refining Rawls's arguments. It is rather to evoke the spatial dimension of justiceövia a notion of spatial justiceöinformed by the charges leveled against Rawls, whose engagement (and liberal political philosophers' in general) with social justice mostly remained as an abstract ideal, `̀ invariably devoid of time and place'' (Merrifield and Swyngedouw, 1997, page 3), and `̀ without the city'' (Katznelson, 1997, page 49). Rawls was obviously weak on the sociospatial front. This might also explain his tendency to ` c̀onceive of individuals as social atoms prior to social relations and institutions'' (Young, 1990, page 27), another source of critique directed against his work, mostly by communitarian scholars (see, for example, Sandel, 1982). Rawls's major concern was the maximization of individual liberty, which would enable indi- viduals to pursue their particular goals in their particular ways without interference. Rights, in his scheme, were used to this end, to foster self-interest, provided that the rights of others are respected. Rawls's moral self, which was prior to social relation- ships, lacked community as constitutive of his or her identity (this situation leads to an `unencumbered self', as Sandel would call it); did not necessarily encourage civic action, and actually contributed to its deterioration (Mouffe, 1992; Skinner, 1992), and his or her `identity' and `differences' went largely unnoticed under a conception of a relatively homogeneous public (Young, 1990). The way in which I try to address this problem diverges my position from that of Young's. Although I draw on her definition of injustice, I do not do so in the name of `difference'. Rather, I turn to Eè tienne Balibar's notion of ëgalibertë (equality ^ freedom) as the ethico-political bond that would inform emancipatory movements, not in the name of a certain particularity, but, rather, in the name of an enactment of equality and freedom. Eè galibertë provides the `universal' bond of solidarity, and more on the notion may be found in the concluding section. Underlying these premises, and indeed the whole endeavour, is the conviction that approaches to, and principles of, justice are time and space specific. A close relation- ship, therefore, between sociospatial specificities and conceptions of justice is assumed. I should like to believe that a sensitivity to the spatial dimension of justice may be developedöespecially in societies where the injustices of spatial dynamics are exposed and largely recognizedöto guide emancipatory movements to suppress domination and oppression in and through space. The city seems to provide a fertile ground for such a prospect. Urban sensibilities The impulses of the 1960s and 1970s were also influential in bringing the `urban question' to the political agenda. Two major reasons for the development of an urban sensibility in this period may be noted. First, there was a growing reaction to the 1788 M Dikec° functional approach to the city, and to the growing emphasis on the city's exchange value to the detriment of its use value. Second, as Alain Bertho (1999) states, there was a search for alternative social movements to the workers movementöfor a polit- ical mobilizing force that was more spatial and urban in nature than the traditional mobilizations based on work. These reasons, of course, may be less confidently stated outside the French political culture. However, it was in this context and for these concerns that Henri Lefebvre conceived the notion of the right to the city. `̀ The right to the city'', Lefebvre (1993, page 435) writes, `̀ cannot be considered a simple visiting right or a return to the traditional city. It can only be formulated as the right to urban life, in a transformed and renewed form.'' It is not simply the right of property owners, in which case policies like zero tolerance might have been legiti- mizedöif not justifiedöbut of all who live in the city. The right to the city, therefore, does not imply a c̀lean' and quaint city where the `good citizens' mingle on its streets, crowding its beautiful parks, and living there happily ever after. As Lefebvre (1996, page 195) argues `̀ it does not abolish confrontations and struggles. On the contrary!'' This, of course, is an unsurprising claim given Lefebvre's conception of the city as the place of simultaneity and encounter, and of rights to be given content through struggle. And he is perfectly sensible to ask the question: `̀ are these not specific urban needs? Is there not also the need for a time for such encounters, such exchanges?'' (1993, page 428). There is, I think, a double message in these questions; an appeal and a critique. The appeal points to the need to (re)claim the right to the city. The critique, on the other hand, stems from Lefebvre's denouncement of the welfare capitalist society as the `̀ bureaucratic society of organized consumption'' where needs are created and institutionalized, where the exchange value of urban space is prioritized over its use value. It was a critique in the context of the 1960s and 1970s when, in France, functionalist and technocratic urbanization processes were under severe critique for eradicating urbanity, and depriving urban dwellers of places of social encounter through the rational ordering of urban space. This critique, in a sense, is a critique of the abstraction of rights from the city, which, I believe, was the motivation for Lefebvre to advance a notion of right to the city. Let me try to clarify this point. A common theme flowing through all the writings of Lefebvre on the city is a critique of the contemporary city, which started to deteriorate in the 19th century with the development and deployment of industrial capitalism and the rise of the modern nation state. In the 20th century, as capitalism dominated all areas of social life, the society was turned into a `bureaucratic society of organized consumption'. Not only consumption was controlled, but the spaces of the society and their production as well, the city being the site where these powers were at work more intensely. In that sense, Lefebvre's attempt can be seen as a political project to rescue the individual from the oppressive and homogenizing processes by asserting his or her right to the city. `̀ The individual does not disappear in the midst of the social effects caused by the pressures of the masses, but is instead affirmed'', he would write. `̀ Certain rights come to light'' (1993, page 435). What, then, happened in the 19th and 20th centuries besides the development and deployment of capitalism, that would lead one to point to the need to reassert rights to the city? And what kind of a right is that; why is Lefebvre so careful to note that it ` c̀annot be considered a simple visiting right''? Let me start with the latter question. Such a conception would bring him too close to the argument Immanuel Kant advanced in his famous text on ``Perpetual peace'' concerning world citizenship and universal hospitality. The stranger, states Kant (1970), cannot claim a right of resi- dence but rather a right of visit. The stranger, upon his or her arrival also enjoys another right, that of hospitality, which suggests that he or she not be treated as an enemy by the host of the territory in question. There is no room for the stranger to Justice and the spatial imagination 1789 claim a right, but simply to enjoy a right to visit or pass through. Besides, this right is conceived as an interstate conditionality, and thus, there is no hospitality for those who do not possess citizenship status in one of the signatory states.(2) The answer to the first question, on the other hand, may be formulated in relation to changing conceptions of citizenship, a notion that has currently been challenged, as, for example, Catherine Wihtol de Wenden (1992) suggests, by two fundamental elements of political context and social tissue: immigration and urbanity. Citizenship originates as rights to the city in a spatial sense, which are now abstracted from the city, from their spatial origins. And this detachment coincides with the periods of which Lefebvre is so critical, and which eventually leads him to proclaim the need to reclaim rights to the city. The city, Engin Isin (1999, page 165) argues, ``has not only been a foreground or a background to struggles for group rights but also a battleground to claim those rights''. These struggles were pursued as `̀ claiming rights to the city as a space of politics'' up until the 17th century, when citizenship and struggles were redirected to center on the state, and eventually, on the modern state since the 19th century. In this sense, Lefebvre's notion of the right to the city is a call to advance an urban spatial approach to political struggles with the participation of all those who inhabit the city without discrimination. `̀ The right to the city, complemented by the right to difference and the right to information, should modify, concretize and make more practical the rights of the citizen as an urban dweller (citadin) and user of multiple services. It would affirm, on the one hand, the right of users to make known their ideas on the space and time of their activities in the urban area; it would also cover the right to the use of the center, a privileged place, instead of being dispersed and stuck into ghettos (for workers, immigrants, the `marginal' and even for the `privileged')'' (1986, page 170; translation from 1996, page 34). The right to the city implies not only the participation of the urban citizen in urban social life, but, more importantly, his or her active participation in the political life, management, and administration of the city. The achievement of these rights, Lefebvre (1986) states, supposes the transformation of the society, of time and space. It is the urban political life which is to be changed, not the city per se. In other words, the right to the city entails not a right to be distributed from above to individuals, but a way of actively and collectively relating to the political life of the city. The urban would then consist of ``a civil society founded not on abstractions but on space and time, as `lived ''' (1986, page 173; emphasis added). The right to the city, therefore, is not simply a participatory right but, more importantly, an enabling right, to be defined and refined through political struggle. It is not only a right to urban space, but to a political space as well, constituting the city as a space of politics. Urban citizenship, in this sense, does not refer to a legal status, but to a form of identification with the city, to a political identity. The construction of this identity through political struggle is enabled by another rightöthe right to difference. The right to difference is complementary to the right of the city. Lefebvre was very clear on this notion, although it somehow ended up with an exclusive focus on differ- ence as particularity. The right to be different, he wrote, is `̀ the right not to be classified forcibly into categories which have been determined by the necessarily homogenizing powers'' (1976a, page 35). His emphasis was on the `be' of the `right to be different', not particularly on the `different' narrowly interpreted as particularity. Therefore, the con- notations were disagreement and contestation (and eventually differing) resulting from a right to `not to subscribe to', and from a `right to be different'. A better translation, perhaps, would be `the right to resist/struggle'. The difference between particularities (2) An elaboration of the notion of hospitality, pointing to the limits and perils of its Kantian version, may be found in Dikec° (forthcoming). 1790 M Dikec° and differences, and the dynamic relation between them were part of Lefebvre's differentialist project. He was critical of the reduction of the differences to the partic- ularities, and the movement from the particularities to the differences was the moment of differing, achieved only through political struggle (Lefebvre, 1981). Solidarity, there- fore, was not built merely around particularities, as Young's (1990) scheme would suggest, for example, but on the will and capabilities to differ. Criticizing the margin- alization of certain groups through identities imposed upon them or through the use of identities that they associate themselves with, and then trying to develop a `politics of identity' in the name of those `differences' to resist such processes, is simply to accept and remain trapped in the already established categories. For Lefebvre particularities existed naturally, but then became difference in the modern world. It is the concept of difference that is created by distanced reflection, and the illusory difference that the individual feels, which, eventually, makes him or her indifferent. He writes (1970a, pages 65 ^ 66): `̀ [D]ifference in act differs ... from the difference merely thought or reflected. The thought and not-lived difference of philosophers and logicians is in opposition with the non-thought and lived difference ... [I]t cannot be reduced to banalized representations: originality, diversity, variety, distinction, etc.'' The right to difference, therefore, is the basis and source of other concrete rights which could `̀ be fully affirmed only beyond the written and the prescribed, in a practice recognized as the basis of social relations'' (1970a, page 45). Differentialism, as he states at the conclusion to his manifesto, `̀ is about living. Not thinking but `being' differently'' (1970a, page 186). Therefore, the rights that Lefebvre conceptualizes are established through lived experience and social relationships, and once established would lead to new ways of life, new social relations, and possibilities to differöeven in relation to the established rights themselves. In this sense, rights, as conceived by Lefebvre, become: `̀ more of a claim upon than a possession held against the world. It becomes a claim upon society for the resources necessary to meet the basic needs and interests of members rather than a kind of property some possess and others do not ... . [I]n terms of rights to the city and rights to political participation, right becomes conceived as an aspect of social relatedness rather than as an inherent and natural property of individuals'' (Holston and Appadurai, 1996, page 197). In claiming these rights, a notion of spatial justice might serve as a mobilizing discourse through the cultivation of a spatial sensibility toward injustice and a spatial culture to fight against it. It might also serve as an ethico-political imperative to avoid the abusive interpretations of these rights, particularly of the right to the city in order to legitimize zero tolerance type of policies. Spatial justice: a conceptualization I begin with three exemplary cases to point to the role of spatialization in the main- tenance and manifestation of injustice. The first one is Harvey's account of the Imperial Foods plant fire in Hamlet. In order to point to the lack of political response to the incident in Hamlet in comparison with one in New York, Harvey writes (1996, page 340; emphasis added): `̀ A similar event in a relatively remote rural setting posed immediate logistical problems for massive on-the-spot political responses (such as the protest demon- stration on Broadway), illustrating the effectiveness of capitalist strategies of geographical dispersal away from politicized central city locations as a means of labor control.'' Justice and the spatial imagination 1791 This was, perhaps, the great lesson that industrial capitalists had learned from the grand strike of July 1969 in Turin, organized by the united syndicates and political parties of the left against increased living costs. The 600 000 workers who united in Turin were not only exploited in the factory, but were dominated in their city as well. Both exploitation and spatial domination were consequences of the logic of the capital- ist mode of accumulation, exploitation was produced and reproduced by social rela- tions of power established under the capitalist production system, and spatial domination was produced and reproduced by the spatial logic of capitalism, contribu- ting further to the domination of a certain group of the population. In this sense, the Turin strike was: `̀ one of the first movements for the right to the city against the pattern in which the city was developed under the pressure of speculation, motivated by the logic of maximum profit'' (Novelli, cited in Lojkine, 1977, page 335). Injustice in the factory was exploitation. Injustice in the city was the domination of urban space, pushing the workers away from the city where rent was no longer affordable. Injustice was at once socially and spatially manifest, and above all, was produced not only socially but spatially as well. The case for the injustice of spatialization was made neither for Hamlet nor Turin. The case, however, was made in the Bus Riders Union (BRU) in Los Angeles, if not explicitly in these terms. The argument was that the Metropolitan Transit Authority's (MTA) transit policies and investment schemes were discriminative against a particular population of transit-dependent bus-riders. The case was brought to court (Labor/ Community Strategy Center versus Los Angeles Metropolitan Transit Authority) as a class action suit on behalf of 350 000 bus riders. It was resolved in 1996 through a consent decree, forcing MTA to reconsider its policies, resulting in a temporary stop of the construction of the planned fixed-rail transit system. What was questioned in the case was the spatial pattern imposed by the MTA on the transit-dependent poor working populations of Los Angeles. In this sense, the BRU: `̀ can be seen as opening traditional notions of civil rights to a more specifically spatial politics revolving around new visions of democratic citizenship and the rights to the city, the rightsöand responsibilitiesöof all urban dwellers to partic- ipate effectively in the social production of their lived cityscapes'' (Soja, 2000, pages 257 ^ 258). Moreover, Soja argues, the BRU case represented an attentiveness to see injustice in its spatial dimension, enticingly signaling the formation of spatially informed practices and politics. What is imminent, perhaps, is the development of a new notion: `̀ I do not mean to substitute spatial justice for the more familiar notion of social justice, but rather to bring out more clearly the potentially powerful yet often obscured spatiality of all aspects of social life and to open up in this spatialized sociality (and historicality) more effective ways to change the world for the better through spatially conscious practices and politics'' (Soja, 2000, page 352). I read these examples as illustrative vignettes that denote both the spatiality of injusticeöfrom physical or locational aspects to more abstract spaces of social and economic relationships that sustain the production of injusticeöand the injustice of spatialityöthe elimination of the possibilities for the formation of political responses (as in the Hamlet case in contrast to the Turin and Los Angeles cases). In the dialectical formulation of the spatiality of injustice and the injustice of spatiality, the spatiality of injustice implies that justice has a spatial dimension to it, and therefore, that a spatial perspective might be used to discern injustice in space (which, of course, can be effectively captured by an analysis of distribution patterns, as the BRU case exemplifies). The injustice of spatiality, on the other hand, implies 1792 M Dikec° existing structures in their capacities to produce and reproduce injustice through space. It is, compared with the spatiality of injustice, more dynamic and process oriented. Such a conceptualization implies two essential points. First, analysis should not be based on the thing under consideration per se, but also on the components of it. Second, form and process are inseparable and should be considered together. How, then, may such an approach be related to space? As Lefebvre puts it: `̀ The dialectic is back on the agenda. But it is no longer Marx's dialectic, just as Marx's was no longer Hegel's ... . The dialectic today no longer clings to historicity and historical time, or to a temporal mechanism such as `thesis-antithesis-synthesis' or `affirmation-negation-negation of the negation'... . To recognize space, to recog- nize what `takes place' there and what it is used for is to resume the dialectic; analysis will reveal the contradictions of space'' (1976a, pages 14 and 17). `̀ (Social) space is not a thing among other things, nor a product among other products ... . It is the outcome of a sequence and set of operations, and thus cannot be reduced to the rank of a simple object ... . Itself the outcome of past actions, social space is what permits fresh actions to occur, while suggesting others and prohibiting yet others'' (1991, page 73). Therefore, the emphasis is not on space per se, but on the processes that produce space, and, at the same time, the implications of these produced spaces on the dynamic processes of social, economic, and political relations. The basic features of the dialec- tical formulation I propose to consider in the relationship between injustice and spatiality are, therefore, as follows: (a) a focus on spatiality as a process; as a producer and reproducer of, and at the same time being produced and reproduced by, relatively stable structures (permanences), (b) recognition of the interrelatedness of injustice and spatiality as producing, repro- ducing, and sustaining each other through a mediation of larger permanences that give rise to both of them. In this sense, the notion of spatial justice is a critique of systematic exclusion, domi- nation, and oppression; a critique aimed at cultivating new sensibilities that would animate actions towards injustice embedded in space and spatial dynamics. The aim is to explicate an ideological discourse on the spatiality of (in)justice, informed by the two notions of the right to the city and the right to difference and resistance, into which such emergent movements as the BRU may insert themselves. Under a larger, but not a totalizing, conception of justice, it is useful to assess the processes that could be the sources and resources of injustice in their specific contexts, as similar processes may produce different consequences in different contexts. Focusing on processes in their relationships and implications would be a reformulated dialectical approach as opposed to focusing on fixed forms or distributive consequences under a universal stencil of justice. Such an approach helps not to discern whether a particular event is just or unjust, but rather, to explore the dynamic processes of social, spatial, economic, and political formations in order to see if they operate in such a way to produce and reproduce dominant and oppressive permanences which would be considered as being unjust. In a spatial sense, domination as a form of injustice manifests itself in space; most visibly in the built environment but also in the other various forms of less visible (or not visible at all) spaces of flows, distributions, networks, and institutions. More importantly, space and the processes of spatialization play a major role not only in the production of the conditions of domination, but also in their reproduction and survival as an indispensable manipulative tool for the existing mode of production (that is, capitalism). How, then, do the three notions I have employed thus faröspatial justice, the right to the city , the right to differenceöcome together as part of an emancipatory politics? Justice and the spatial imagination 1793 In what follows, I shall offer a `triad' that brings together these notions, and defines the parameters of a spatially informed emancipatory politics. At this point, I still remain vulnerable to charges that the argument about these notions is too abstract, and that the term `emancipation' continues to be unpleasantly ambiguous. I attend to these issues by presenting the case of French urban policy in the next section, focusing particularly on a law passed in 1991 in order to fight against the problem of socio- spatial exclusion. The case presents an opportunity for the articulation of the notions of spatial justice, the right to the city, and the right to difference, and demonstrates a context in which the injustice of spatial dynamics is recognized. The observations drawn from the case form the basis of a spatial politics of emancipation, which I clarify in the concluding section drawing from Balibar and Rancie© re. The triad consists of three notions: the spatial dialectics of injustice (the spatiality of injustice and the injustice of spatiality), the right to the city, and the right to difference. I articulate these notions as the parameters of an `ideal of ëgalibertë' (equal- ity ^ freedom); that is, the suppression of domination and repression, achievement of which would imply a moment of emancipation. The argument is that Lefebvre's two rights, which have been the subject of much intellectual effort aimed at emancipatory politics, provide a better framework when articulated with a `spatial dialectics of injustice'. This, indeed, seems to be a necessary underpinning in order to resolve the paradox rising from decidedly individualistic versus collective interpretations of these rights (for example, zero tolerance versus À city center for all').(3) Such an approach is informed not only by the premise that spatial dynamics play an essential role in the production and reproduction of injustice, but also by the premise that they permit, as well as prohibit, the formation of rights claims and the ways and extent to which rights are put into action and practised. The triad provides a common lexicon(4) and conceptual apparatus, which then could cultivate an ` èthico-political bond'' (Mouffe, 1992, page 231), or an `̀ ethics of political solidarity'' (Harvey, 1996, page 360) to inform emancipatory movements of those(5) who are, to name a few, `̀ trapped in space'' (Harvey, 1989), ` c̀hained to a place'' (Bourdieu, 1999), `̀ disabled by the social production of space'' (Gleeson, 1998), excluded by urban entrepreneurialism (Hall and Hubbard, 1996), or expelled through urban renewal projects (Leroux, 2001). The bond is ethical in the sense that it is nurtured through social relatedness, rather than assumed as an ontological given. Such a con- ception is necessary to imply that forms of morally defensible practices must be socially negotiated, through engagement, rather than being manipulated by the anxieties of dominant groups in the city. And the bond is political in the sense that it entails antagonism and contestation, and not always an effortless reconciliation, for the simple reason that the very production of space is decidedly political (see, for example, Lefebvre, 1976b). As for the way in which the individual components of the triad relate to one another, the notion of spatial (in)justice sets the parameters by which the right to the city may be assessed, violations of which are resisted through a right to difference. (3) À city center for all' is an association in Marseille, currently fighting against speculative forces generated by urban renewal projects, which force out the immigrant population from the city center. See Leroux (2001). (4) Michael Keith (1997) employs a similar notionö`vocabulary of resistance'öin his work on young Bengalis in London's East End, and shows how such a common lexicon serves as a bond in their struggle against racism. (5) This, of course, must not be interpreted as implying merely `those who are affected', but be seen in the light of the notion of ëgalibertë. In this sense, these movements represent a resistance against the negation of socially enshrined principles (in this case, of the suppression of discrimination and exclusion), against the negation of humanity as such (Balibar, 1997). This is the universal bond that coalesces not only those who are affected, but all who wish to negate the negation of humanity. 1794 M Dikec° And there is good reason to believe that such a spatial sensitivity to (in)justice may be developed, especially in societies, such as France, where the spatial dynamics of social exclusion are widely recognized. David Miller's thesis endorses this likelihood, according to which people: `̀ hold conceptions of social justice as part of more general views of society, and ... acquire these views through their experience of living in actual societies with definite structures and embodying particular kinds of interpersonal relationship'' (1976, page 342). It is now timely to introduce the French case to demonstrate the ways in which these rights may be articulated with a `spatial dialectics of injustice'öinjustice understood as domination and repressionöand how such an articulation may inform emancipatory politicsöemancipation understood as the suppression of domination and repression. Right to the city: beyond homage to Lefebvre? `̀ The political strategy implies: a) Introducing the urban problematic into (French) political life, pushing it to the forefront; b) Elaborating a program of which the first article will be widespread self-manage- ment [autogestion]...; c) Introducing... the `right to the city'.'' Henri Lefebvre, `̀ Towards an urban strategy'' (1970b, page 199) French urban policy, Daniel Bëhar (1999) wrote, has probably been the most commented upon public policy of the last fifteen years. What he refers to here, it should be noted, is not French urban policy in general, but a particular one that was initiated in the 1980s with the `spatialization of social policies' (Bertho, 1996; 1999; Chaline, 1998), and regrouped later in 1988 under the generic term la politique de la ville as a national urban policy. The use of the term `urban policy' hereafter refers to this specific policy. The attempt here is not to provide a full account of French urban policy, but, rather, to take this policy by way of an example in order to; first, make more concrete what the dialectical formulation between injustice and spatialityöthat is, spatiality of injustice and injustice of spatialityöimplies; second, to illustrate how some of the notions discussed in abstract ways, such as the right to the city, are implied in urban policy; and, third, to consider some possible implications of the notion of spatial justice for urban policy in general. The origins of urban policy go back to the first Housing and Social Life plan of 1977 (Habitat et vie sociale), which was originally conceived for the restoration of large housing blocks (grands ensembles) built by the state to meet the housing short- age in the 1960s (the period during which Lefebvre conceived the notion of the right to the city). Since then, with policies such as the 1981 Social Development of Neigh- bourhoods (Dëveloppement social des quartiers), which, in 1989, became Urban Social Development (Dëveloppement social urbain), the main focus of urban policy in the French state's fight against exclusion (for which a city minister was appointed in 1991) has been the most deprived areas of cities (`quartiers en difficultë'). Urban policy has been largely affected by political changes and incidents of vio- lence, being modified by all successive governments, and today it is recognized that it has become quite complex and difficult to assess in terms of effectiveness. Originally developed around the idea to identify and rehabilitate `neighborhoods in difficulty', the concern of urban policy today is `̀ no longer a question of curbing urban violence and restoring a few degraded housing blocks that are poorly situated'' (Lelëvrier, 1999, page 35). Today the underlying problem is defined as segregation and exclusion. Justice and the spatial imagination 1795 The two basic notions around which urban policy is conceived are concentration and exclusion (Lelëvrier, 1999). The `urban and social degradation' is largely attributed to the concentration of `problem populations' in certain areasömainly the large housing blocksöa situation which aggravates the marginalization of individuals. Such a concentration is seen to contribute further to the problem of exclusion. Regard- ing the notion of exclusion, a key work has been that of Lenoir (1974), who showed that exclusion was not simply limited to a few victims of economic circumstances, but was a structural problem with its own dynamics. Exclusion, in other words, was not merely an economic question, but a social and urban one as well. As Daniel Bëland and Randall Hansen (2000, page 55) state, `̀ while the long-term unemployed are the archetypal example of les exclus, they are not the sole example. The concept of l'exclusion is meant also to describe a multi- plicity of situations in which the individual is prevented from participating, even temporarily, in society.'' Defining the problem as one of exclusion is to recognize; first, the spatial (abstract and concrete) dimension of the problem; and second, the presence of a group of the included against which the category of the excluded may be defined. This implies that there exists a process of exclusion that actually leaves certain individuals and groups outside the category of the included. The process, of course, has many dimen- sions, and could be approached from a variety of epistemological and methodological perspectives. There is, however, an important dimension to it which has recently been largely recognized in the growing literature on exclusion: the spatial dimension (see, for example, Byrne, 1999; Madanipour, 1998). The spatial dimension of exclusion is also recognized in the French policy circles. The `exclusion problem' entered the agenda of public debate in the 1980s, during the period in which urban policy was conceived. The effect of this conception on urban policy has been an awareness that: `̀ the social division between those who are in or out became an `urban division' between `normal', `ordinary' neighborhoods and èxclusion' neighborhoods which concentrate the misfortunes of our society. Those who are èxcluded' from society become `excluded from the city''' (Lelëvrier, 1999, page 35; emphasis added). Those who are èxcluded', in other words, are also deprived of their rights to the city. French society was moving, in the words of Alain Touraine (1991, page 12), from a `̀ society of discrimination'' to a `̀ society of segregation''. The notion of segregation was effective to capture the spatial dynamics and manifestations of the social exclusion problem, a problem of which elimination was one of the major missions of the first City Minister, Michel Delebarre, in 1991. The Urban Development Act of 13 July 1991 (Loi d'orientation sur la ville, known as LOV, also as the anti-ghetto law) was conceived with these concerns in mind. The LOV was published in the official journal (Journal Officiel de la Rëpublique Franc° aise) on 19 July 1991, and the first article read: `̀ In order to realize the right to the city, urban districts, other territorial collectivities and their groupings, the State and its public institutions assure to all the inhabi- tants of cities conditions of living and dwelling promoting social cohesion as to avoid or abate the phenomena of segregation. This policy must provide for the insertion of each neighborhood [quartier] in the city and assure the coexistence of diverse social categories in each agglomeration. The reverberation of Lefebvre's conceptualization of the right to the city is clear: `̀ To exclude the urban from groups, classes, individuals, is also to exclude them from civilization, if not from society itself. The right to the city legitimates the refusal to allow oneself to be removed from urban reality by a discriminatory and segregative organization'' (Lefebvre, 1996, page 195). 1796 M Dikec° However, the LOV was vulnerable to the criticism that it was implicitly envisioning `̀ a correspondence between residential mixity and social harmony'' (Simon, 1995, page 30). In this case, French urban policymakers made not one mistake, but two: trying to resolve some kind of perceived spatiality of injustice (that is, segregation and the resulting deprivation of the right to the city), and failing, in this attempt, to conceptualize the problem and conceive policies around the structural dynamics of a mode of spatial organization that constantly produces injustice öif not here, some- where else. The question is not whether or not at some point some form of injustice is spatially manifested. The question is whether or not this spatially manifested injustice is produced and reproduced spatially (as well as socially). And the question that follows is this: what are the spatial dynamics, in the production and persistence, of this injustice? This is the interplay between the spatiality of injustice and the injustice of spatiality. If one holds the hypothesis that space is socially producedöand is not simply a containeröthere are important implications to be drawn from the `segregation problem': segregation is not a question of distribution in space, but of spatialization itself. It is the very structural dynamics of the spatial organization processes in the cityöand not simply some `distributive force' external to space, distributing each to his or her `proper' place. And these dynamics; first, contribute to the formation of such segregated areas with a concentration of poverty; second, force a certain group of the population to locate in these places, making it even more difficult for the individuals to participate in the society; and third, further reduce the chances of relocating not only for the immediate population, but, perhaps, for the generations to come unless the spatial dynamics are modified. In other words, such spaces are not simply by-products, mirrors, or stages of various forms of injustice; they are constituted by and constitutive of them. The basic idea behind the 1991 LOV, then, has been to `integrate' or `insert' the èxcluded' into the city through urban policies. Such a conception, of course, was vulnerable to charges on many fronts. Two of them, at least, seem too important to be overlooked. First, designation and delimitation of `problem areas' further contribute to the stigmatization and victimization of the population living in those areas. And second, the logic of `insertion' or `integration', clearly derived from the republican ideal of the one and indivisible French Republic, implies assimilation, on the one hand, and hostile partitioning of the society, on the other (for further discussion of these issues, see, among others, Baudou|« , 2000; Bertho, 1996; 1999; Faber, 2000). In addition to these, the notion of the right to the city, which opens the LOV as the first article, is not clear as to its implications. The temporary residents' situation, for example, is totally ambiguous as no attempt was made to link this notion with the notion of citizenship. The use of this notion, therefore, seemed merely `̀ a homage to the work of Henri Lefebvre''.(6) This was a sensible assessment; the catchphrase, without deliberate elab- oration and careful consideration of larger structural issues, appeared unable to deliver its promises. A letter was then circulated on 31 July 1991 to clarify the articles of the law, which stated that the opening article had `̀ no normative nature''.(7) The pursuit of a right to the city, which would imply a major reconsideration of the dynamics of both urban space (for example, property market, housing and land-use policies) and the demos (that is, citizenship), was therefore repudiated. (6) When the LOV was in preparation, a seminar was organized that brought together law-makers, researchers, and scholars. The minutes of the seminar were then published in Recherches 20 `̀ Loi d'orientation pour la ville: sëminaire chercheurs dëcideurs'' (Paris, Ministe© re de l'ëquipement, des transports et du logement, 1991). The comment was made by Vëronique De Rudder, page 36. References below to Balibar (1991) are also from this seminar. (7) See Circulaire no. 91-57 relative a© la loi d'orientation pour la ville no. 91-662 du 13 juillet 1991. Justice and the spatial imagination 1797 As important as these criticisms are, there are significant implications of the way in which urban policy is conceived in France. First, the state has recognized that the mode of urban spatial organization, inter alia, deprives certain individuals and groupsöidentifiable not only socially but spatially as wellöof their rights to the city, which are yet to be given content. Second, with the `̀ territorialization of social policies on the terrain of the city'' (Bertho, 1996, page 107), French urban policymakers, implicitly or explicitly, `̀ accept[ed] certain cause and effect relationships between the city and forms of `social disorder'' (Lelëvrier, 1999, page 35), with a hope, perhaps, of `̀ changing life through changing the city'' (Lëgë, 1995, page 34). The social and the spatial, in other words, were conceived to be mutually affecting each other in the production and aggravation of various social problems as well as in the attempts to resolve them. This point opens the way into a discussion of the notion of spatial justiceöthe particularities, flaws, and effectiveness of the policy notwithstanding. What flows from this point, however, is not that spatial interventions will automati- cally solve social problems in the city. Such a conviction has already been realized as a problem with urban policy in France (see, for example, Bëhar, 1999; Bertho, 1996). The important point is that the production and persistence of social problems in the city are largely affected by modes and forms of spatial organization. There is enough evidence to note that intensification of social inequalities in space is accompanied by a stabilization of the conditions of the concentration of poverty (Bëhar, 1999). Spatial dynamics, therefore, not only aggravate, but actually produce injustice through the stabilization of social inequalities and problems, becoming a major reproducer of them. Seen in this way, urban policy `̀ is no longer confronted merely with circum- stances of the absolute concentration of poverty, but with a multiplicity of territorial dynamics of social devalorization'' (Bëhar, 1999, page 216; emphasis added). The con- clusion to be drawn from these remarks is simple: if the problems of inequality, exclusion, segregation, and social devalorization enter the sociopolitical agenda as concerns of justice, it is as important to consider the ways in which: first, such problems are manifested spatially; and second, and more importantly, such problems are produced and reproduced spatially, through the very production of space. Injustice and its persistence, in this sense, is the product of spatial dynamics. One more point needs to be emphasized. Segregation is an intrinsic part of urban spatialization, and in no way unique to France. Besides, segregation does not intrinsi- cally carry a negative connotation; its prohibition may also be coercive (see, for example, Young, 1999). In this sense, the LOV may be charged by arguing that it was premised on a `mythical ideology of good mixity', treating segregation merely as a result to the neglect of the fact that it is voluntarily created as well [Rëmi Baudou|« , Director of ACIV (Action Concertëe Incitative Ville) at the Ministe© re de la Recherche, Paris, personal interview 26 June 2001]. However, the French case makes clear that there exists a population, living in poor conditions compared with other parts of the city, which is at once socially excluded and spatially segregated, and not always voluntarily. The point here is about segregation as a spatial mode of social exclusion as it relates to concentration of poverty in certain areas, as one of the structural dynamics of social exclusion; that is, the social processes and spatial practices that produce and reproduce socially excluded groups. Therefore, an intervention is necessary `̀ on the principles and norms of urban practices that produce socio-spatial exclusion'' (Bëhar, 1995, page 13). Seen in this way, `̀ the `pathology' of these particular neighborhoods is due less to their mono-func- tionality or to their social specialization than to the rigidity of urban forms that hinder ordinary processes of social appropriation and temporal evolution'' (Bëhar, 1995, page 14). 1798 M Dikec° The problem, in other words, is not `̀ a simple phenomenon of localized exclusion'' (Lëgë, 1995, page 42). Such a conceptualization of the problem would be the spatiality of injustice, in a static sense, which could probably have been addressed, if not with complete success, by policies of `integration'. This, however, is not the case. The socio- spatial exclusion problem is constantly produced and reproduced by the ways in which the society is spatially organized, by ways that defy the rehabilitative capabilities of urban policies conceived to remedy the situation. This, precisely, is what is implied by the notion of injustice of spatiality, which draws attention to the structural dynamics of spatial practices as sources and resources of unjust sociospatial practices and/or their unjust consequences. The interplay between the twoöspatiality of injustice and the injustice of spatialityöis important as it implies that although the spatiality of injustice may be captured as a snapshot, so to speak, of spatial practices (for example, segregated neighborhoods, public transportation network, the dominated city center, etc), the policies and actions conceived to address the issue should take into consideration the structural dynamics of spatialization (for example, the organization of property markets, housing, rent, and tax policies, etc), which the notion of the injustice of spatiality tries to capture. This is to reconcile the tension between overvalorizing and overlooking distributional issues. The focus, therefore, is not merely on how spatializa- tion affects distribution, but also on how it stabilizes distributional patterns. Promoting (through, for example, land-use policies, housing market arrangements, entrepreneurial strategies, etc) or simply not interfering withöand therefore allowing the persistence of dynamics of structural exclusionöspatial practices that draw rigid boundaries and that cause and contribute to the domination and repression of certain groups, and then asking questions about social justice ignores the structural spatial dynamics of injustice. The production of space, in this sense, has to be at the core of any examination of injustice for it plays an essential role not only in distribution but also in production and reproduction. Thus, in the French case, it was a certain form of spatialization that contributed largely to the production of the socially excluded. It was, moreover, this form of spatialization that kept them excluded, reproducing the exclusionary processes. Conclusions: politicizing the urban spatial `̀ Space is a doubt: I have constantly to mark it, to designate it. It's never mine, never given to me, I have to conquer it.'' Georges Perec (1997, page 91) `̀ In the case of ideologies of what is good and right it may be space rather than time that is crucial. Something may be good and just everywhere, somewhere, here or elsewhere.'' Goren Therborn (cited in Cresswell, 1996, page 3) `̀ The limits of just and unjust'', Voltaire once wrote, `̀ are very difficult to set down; like the middle state between health and illness, between the appropriateness and inap- propriateness of things, between the false and true, is difficult to mark'' (1961, page 913). It would, similarly, be very difficult, and hardly desirable, to discern the line between justice and injustice as they relate to spatial practices. For this reason, perhaps, it is best to conceive the notion of spatial justice, with the rights to the city and difference, in relation to a `universality of an ideal', as exemplified by Balibar's proposition of ëgalibertë (equality ^ freedom). Eè galibertë signifies the unconditional `differential' push in the collective process of struggle for the suppression of discrimination and repression. Balibar (1997) defines èquality' as nondiscrimination, and `freedom' as nonconstraint (nonrepression), both of which remain open to diverse determinations depending on the circumstances. Elim- inating or simply fighting against discrimination necessarily implies the elimination Justice and the spatial imagination 1799 or the fight against repression and vice versa (the impossibility of freedom without equality and of equality without freedom). Hence the notion of ëgalibertë. The joint suppression of discrimination and repression implies emancipation. Balibar's propo- sition, as a politics of emancipation, has important implications for the current project for two major reasons. First, ëgalibertë, as an ideal of nondiscrimination and non- repression, remains as an indestructible resource of insurrection against the existing order, reborn and re-experienced in diverse situations, places, groups, etc. It is achieved through a collective process, through a political struggle `against oppression, social hierarchies, and inequalities'. Equality and freedom, in this collective process of the suppression of discrimination and repression, therefore, ``can never be granted, distributed among individuals, they can only be conquered'' (Balibar, 1997, page 446; emphasis added). This has close resonance with Lefebvre's differentialism and the rights to the city and difference, for both rights are constantly redefined and acquired through political struggle, and they are not procedural and normative in nature. The ideal, then, is to conquer, through a collective process, the spaces (the right to the city) and means (the right to difference) of this struggle. In this sense, the resonance with ëgalibertë would be thus: the right of all city habitants to participate in the political life of the city (fighting against discrimination), and their right to political struggle of resistance (fighting against repression). What is implied is not simply a political movement, but a transformation of the political itself. What is implied is a right to politics, meaning that ``no one can ever be emancipated from outside or from above, but only by his/her own action and its collectivization'' (Balibar, 1997, page 446). Jacques Rancie© re (1995, page 70), in this sense, was perfectly sensible to state that ``the question is not only `How are we to face a political problem?' but `How are we to reinvent politics?'''. The second implication of Balibar's ëgalibertë has to do with the notion'söas a universality of an idealötransindividual nature. This does not only refer to a collective process of struggle against discrimination and repression, but also to its universal symbolic dimension as a politics of emancipation, which means that `̀ it does not depend on the extension of its influence or its popularity'' (1997, page 447). The struggle, therefore, is not aimed at defending `̀ the rights of a particular group in the name of that particularity itself, but [at] proclaiming that the discrimination or exclu- sion that strikes that particular group represents a negation of humanity as such'' (1997, page 453). What is changed, at the end of the day, is the very political itself: the struggle does not delineate an identity-defined community but a solidarity in the collective process of the elimination of discrimination and repression, in achieving ëgalibertë, which always remains as the element of subversion of the existing order. In order to discern more clearly the implications of ëgalibertë as they relate to the arguments advanced in this paper, it would be helpful to consider Balibar's reflections on the French LOV presented above, focusing particularly on his remarks on the right to the city. According to Balibar (1991, page 65), any notion of right necessarily implies some realization of equality and freedom, or, better yet, `̀ some way of defining and instituting the balance between equality and freedom''. Although the reference to equality is explicit in the LOV, there is no reference to freedom: it is largely presup- posed under the conditions of the free market. In other words, how this right (the right to the city)öequally distributedöwill be freely enjoyed by all city inhabitants (although the status of noncitizens and temporary residents is totally ambiguous) remains overlooked. The allusion to equality in the LOV, however, is not without problems. It suffers from an ambiguity, caused by the oscillation between two conceptions of equality: arithmetical (egalitarian) and qualified or proportional equality. In this sense, the 1800 M Dikec° law sometimes implies an ``egalitarian redistribution of a service or an indivisible good, situated beyond individual property, that in sum would be the urban as such, or the quality of urban life''. Sometimes, however, it implies a conception of equality that would ``attribute each individual or group a good corresponding to its rank; that is, to its financial means, and material and cultural needs'' (Balibar, 1991, page 66). What will equally be granted to individuals or groups, in other words, is not clear. The former conception would probably demand a definition as to the meanings `urban' or `quality of urban life', which would then be assumed to be enjoyed by all inhabitants. The state's role then would be to provide the desired qualities (including quantity) of the service in question or urban life in general. (`Here is a beautiful city for you, enjoy it!') The latter would probably imply defining some form of criteria and ensuring the `rules of the game' according to which each individual or group would get their due (`You are eligible for social housing, but feel free to join the gentrificators in the city center should your financial situation improve'). Both positions are premised on a notion of the right to be defined and granted `from above'. Balibar, however, has in mind a third notion of equality, neither distributive nor participatory, but an openly civic one (a new ethics and politics). Informed by such a conception of equality, he argues, ``talking about the right to the city would be a way of indicating that the city becomes as such a polis, a political collectivity, a place where public interest is defined and realized'' (1991, page 66). Is this not what Lefebvre also had in mind with his notion of the right to the city complemented by the right to difference? Such a perspective above all implies a conception of the city that goes beyond an administrative entity, and makes it the place in and over which the terms of the right, or, better still, the nature of relationships between state, society and its space are negotiated. The right to the city implies not only a formulation of certain rights and the cultivation of the political among city habitants, but also a reconsideration of the spatial dynamics that make the city. Therefore, it should not be conceived merely as a practice of claiming and asserting rights, but should also be conceptualized in a way that puts on the agenda the dynamics (such as property markets) and principles (such as urban policy, land-use policy, planning laws, etc) of the ways in which social relations are spatialized in the city. The triad I propose, in this sense, is an attempt to address this issue via a notion of spatial justice that calls into question the dynamics and principles which manifest themselves spatially in the city. Besides, it seems necessary, should the Lefebvrian notion be used, to conceptualize a notion of spatial justice in order to be able to distinguish between appropriation and domination of urban space in the name of a right to the city. Neil Smith's (1997, page 134) example of the claim of and the counterclaim against homeless people, both of which appeal to the same source for justification, exposes `̀ the doubleness inherent in the system of abstract justice based on individual rights''. The claim of homeless people poses the following question: `̀ Why do we as homeless individuals have no right to housing?'' The counterclaim, against this, and using the same source of appeal, presses another question: `̀ Don't I have a right to live without homeless people messing up the neighborhood?'' The first question, as Smith states, is `̀ over and against individualism'' whereas the second stands for a `̀ reasserted individu- alism''. This is a remarkable example for it depicts the perils of a right to the city discourse interpreted in the liberal framework of individual rights. The notion of a right to the city implies not only a spatial change, but a societal one as well, for the ways in which the notion is conceived and justified depends largely on the society itself, its political culture included. In other words, the right to the city might vary drastically depending on the society in question, especially if the demos is marked with clear and Justice and the spatial imagination 1801 rigid demarcations. In the Greek polis, for example, the right to the city was arguably practised perfectly with the exception of women and slaves. To take a recent example, there is nothing to prevent the Mayor of New York Rudolph Giuliani from advancing a `right to the city' (for some but not for others), and enforcing zero tolerance policies in its name, unless a new societal ethics is cultivated by the living togetherness of all city inhabitants. How, then, could one overcome this paradox, and conceive a right to the city (and to difference as well) as part of an emancipatory politics? Through the `heterology of emancipation', I would argue following Rancie© re that, ``the logic of political subjectivization, of emancipation'', ``is a heterology, a logic of the other, ... it is never the simple assertion of an identity'' (1995, page 68). Even the workers' movement was not an assertion of identity. Proletarii, in Latin, meant ``prolific people''ö``people who make children, who merely live and reproduce with- out a name, without being counted as part of the symbolic order of the city''. Proletarians, therefore, did not imply a particular identity; it was rather `̀ the name of anyone, the name of the outcast: those who do not belong to the order of castes, indeed, those who are involved in undoing this order'' (Rancie© re, 1995, page 67). There- fore, their movement, as one of emancipation, did not imply a selfish reassertion of individuality, but an enactment of equality and freedom. `̀ One can object that the idea of emancipation is historically related to the idea of the self in the formula of `self-emancipation of workers'. But the first motto of any self- emancipation movement is always the struggle against `selfishness'. This is not only a moral statement (for instance, the dedication of the individual to the militant community); it is also a logical one: the politics of emancipation is the politics of the self as an other, or, in Greek terms, a heteron. The logic of emancipation is a heterology'' (Rancie© re, 1995, page 65). Seen in this way, ëgalibertë, as an enactment of equality and freedom, provides the universal that transcends particular identifications. The triad I have offered, in this sense, defines the spatial parameters of a struggle against discrimination and repre- ssion. The formation of a sensibility to the spatial dimension of injustice (for example in the French case mentioned above) could be considered as a transcendence of tensions rising from particular group interests in the city (segregation, sociospatial exclusion, etc) through a universality as an ideal, through the development of a con- sciousness nurtured by living together and sharing space, and through a (civic) ideal of ëgalibertë. If the city remains a site of structural sociospatial exclusion, where domi- nation is legimated, not only does such a consciousness remain undeveloped, but, worse still, it remains misdeveloped; that is, it gives rise to sociospatial exclusion in and against the city. All this is not to imply that the city, through its evolution, has not been the site of exclusion and segregation. Neglecting this fact would be a nostalgic fallacy. Legitimating, even fostering, this fact, however, would be a fatal flaw, engen- dering zero tolerance type of politics. How, then, would the formation of such a consciousness contribute to the struggle against injustice? How could a spatially informed and sensible politics of resistance use space in the fight against injustice? How, in other words, could a spatial content be given to such a politics of emancipation? Four approaches, following Garber (2000, pages 267 ^ 269), may be distinguished, which, of course, are not mutually exclusive, and which could also work against emancipatory (ëgalibertë) movements. A politics of resistance could use urban space in particular ways so that; first, people act from space, politically mobilizing from the material conditions of their space, and seek alternative spatializations (for example, the Paris Commune, the Los Angeles riots, the Turin strike, the BRU case); second, people act on space, to appropriate or to dominate it with a group identity (for example, appropriation of the Tompkins Square Park in New York, but also the formation of 1802 M Dikec° gated communities); third, people act in space, taking it to the streets for debates, displays, protests or violence (for example, the Paris Commune, May 1968, the Los Angeles riots, the Turin strike); and finally, people make space, creating the conditions to expand the public political involvement through the linking of metaphorical space and politics (for example, in Harvey's account above, the formation of a political response in New York, but not in Hamlet, the organization of the BRU case). Although space most often appears as a means of control and domination, for this very reason it also carries the seeds of significant resistance (Cresswell, 1996). What, then, are the substantive implications of the notion of spatial justice? Two mutually constitutive prospects may be discerned. First, it might provide a conceptual apparatus that could be given normative content to guide the actual production of urban space. Second, its discursive development and deployment might inform emancipatory politics willing to confront spatial dynamics that produce and reproduce various forms of injustice. Both prospects, of course, will depend on the society in question, and the meanings attached to principles of justice. Justice, after all, is a contingent `̀ reification of commensurability'' (Dimock, 1997, page 6), not an ontological given. Acknowledgements. This paper was originally conceived for a seminar on planning theory taken with Edward Soja in the Department of Urban Planning, UCLA, Spring 1999. I am indebted to him for the initial idea for this project, for his sustained encouragement, as well as for many useful and pleasant discussions. I have also enjoyed the comments from and friendships of Rëmi Baudou|« , Julie-Anne Boudreau, Marco Cenzatti, Liette Gilbert, and Raymond Rocco. Three anonymous referees provided challenging criticisms and much appreciated suggestions. All responsibility, it goes without saying, remains mine. Parts of this essay were drafted while I was a participant in UCLA's Paris Program in Critical Theory. The generous financial support of the Program and of UCLA's Urban Planning Department is gratefully acknowledged. References Balibar Eè , 1991, comments in the minutes of a seminar, in `̀ Loi d'orientation pour la ville: sëminaire chercheurs dëcideurs'' Recherches 20 Balibar Eè ,1997 La craintedes masses: politiqueetphilosophieavantetapre© s Marx [The fearof masses: politics and philosophy before and after Marx] (Galilëe, Paris) Baudou|« R, 2000, `̀ Baª tir la ville du troisie© me me millënaire: regards sur les politiques urbaines franc° aises et la question du multiculturalisme'' [Building the city of the third millennium: thoughts on French urban policies and the question of multiculturalism], paper presented at the Cities and Cultural Diversity in France and the Francophone World Symposium, organized by the French Department of University of California, Los Angeles; a translated version also appeared in Critical Planning 7(2), 117 ^ 126 Bëhar D, 1995, `̀ Banlieues ghettos, quartiers populaires ou ville ëclatëe? L'espace urbain a© l'ëpreuve de la nouvelle question sociale'' [Ghetto suburbs, working class neighborhoods or fragmented city? Urban space put to test by the new social question] Les Annales de la recherche urbaine 68 ^ 69 7 ^ 14 Bëhar D, 1999, `̀ En finir avec la politique de la ville?'' [Putting an end to urban policy?] Esprit 258 209 ^ 218 Bëland D, Hansen R, 2000, `̀ Reforming the French welfare state: solidarity, social exclusion and the three crises of citizenship'' West European Politics 23(1) 47 ^ 64 Bertho A, 1996 La Crise de la politique: du dësarroi militant a© la politique de la ville [A crisis in policymaking: from militant disarray to urban policy] (L'Harmattan, Paris) Bertho A, 1999 Contre l'Eè tat, la politique [Policymaking against the state] (La Dispute, Paris) Bourdieu P,1999,`̀ Site effects'', inTheWeight of theWorld: Social Suffering in Contemporary Society Ed. P Bourdieu, translated by P P Ferguson, S Emanuel, J Johnson, S T Waryn (Stanford University Press, Stanford, CA) pp 123 ^ 129; originally published in1993 as La mise© redu monde (Eè ditions du Seuil, Paris) Boyne G, Powell M, 1991,``Territorial justice: a review of theory and evidence'' Political Geography Quarterly 10 263 ^ 281 Byrne D, 1999 Social Exclusion (Open University Press, Buckingham) Chaline C, 1998 Les politiques de la ville [Urban policies] 2nd edition (Presses Universitaires de France, Paris) Justice and the spatial imagination 1803 Circulaire no. 91-57 relative a© la loi d'orientation pour la ville no. 91-662 du 13 juillet 1991 [Letter no. 91-57 relative to the urban development act no. 91-662 13 July 1991] Ministe© re de l'ëquipement, des transports et du logement, Direction de l'architecture et de l'urbanisme, Direction de la Construction (Paris: 31 juillet 1991) Cresswell T, 1996 In Place/Out of Place: Geography, Ideology, and Transgression (University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, MN) Davies B, 1968 Social Needs and Resources in Local Services (Michael Joseph, London) Dikec° M, 2001, `̀ Geography and social justice: three decades later'', manuscript, Department of Urban Planning, University of California, Los Angeles, CA Dikec° M, forthcoming, `̀ Pera peras poros: longings for spaces of hospitality'' Theory, Culture and Society Dimock W C, 1997 Residues of Justice: Literature, Law, Philosophy (University of California Press, Berkeley, CA) Faber J, 2000 Les indësirables: l'intëgration a© la franc° aise [The undesirables: integration in the French way] (Grasset, Paris) Flusty S, 1994 Building Paranoia: The Proliferation of Interdictory Space and The Erosion of Spatial Justice (LA Forum for Architecture and Urban Design,West Hollywood, CA) Garber J A, 2000, `̀ The city as a heroic public sphere'', in Democracy, Citizenship and the Global City Ed. E Isin (Routledge, London) pp 257 ^ 274 Gleeson B, 1998, `̀ Justice and the disabling city'', in Cities of Difference Eds R Fincher, J M Jacobs (Guilford Press, New York) pp 89 ^ 119 Hall T, Hubbard P, 1996, `̀ The entrepreneurial city: new urban politics, new urban geographies?'' Progress in Human Geography 20 153 ^ 174 Harvey D, 1973 Social Justice and the City (Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, MD) Harvey D, 1989 The Urban Experience (Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, MD) Harvey D, 1992, `̀ Social justice, postmodernism and the city'' International Journal of Urban and Regional Research 16 588 ^ 601 Harvey D, 1996 Justice, Nature and the Geography of Difference (Blackwell, Malden, MA) Holston J, Appadurai A, 1996, `̀ Cities and citizenship'' Public Culture 8(2) 187 ^ 204 Isin E, 1999, `̀ Introduction: cities and citizenship in a global age'' Citizenship Studies 3(2) 165 ^ 172 Journal Officiel de la Rëpublique Franc° aise [Official Journal of the French Republic] 19 Juillet 1991 Kant I, 1970, `̀ Perpetual peace: a philosophical sketch'', in Kant's Political Writings Ed. H Reiss, translated by H B Nisbet (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge) pp 93 ^ 130; first published 1795 Katznelson I, 1997, `̀ Social justice, liberalism and the city: considerations on David Harvey, John Rawls and Karl Polanyi'', in The Urbanization of Injustice Eds A Merrifield, E Swyngedouw (New York University Press, New York) pp 45 ^ 64 Keith M, 1997, `̀ Street sensibility? Negotiating the political by articulating the spatial'', in The Urbanization of Injustice Eds A Merrifield, E Swyngedouw (New York University Press, New York) pp 137 ^ 160 Lefebvre H, 1970a Le manifeste diffërentialiste [Differentialist manifesto] (Gallimard, Paris) Lefebvre H, 1970b La rëvolution urbaine [The urban revolution] (Gallimard, Paris) Lefebvre H, 1976a The Survival of Capitalism: Reproduction of the Relations of Production translated by F Bryant (Allison and Busby, London); first published 1973 Lefebvre H, 1976b, `̀ Reflections on the politics of space''Antipode 8 30 ^ 37 Lefebvre H, 1981 Critique de la vie quotidienne III: De la modernitë au modernisme (Pour une mëtaphilosophie du quotidien) [Critique of everyday life III. From modernity to modernism (for a metaphilosophy of the everyday)] (L'Arche ëditeur, Paris) Lefebvre H, 1986 Le Retour de la Dialectique [The return of dialectics] (Messidor/Eè ditions sociales, Paris) Lefebvre H, 1991 The Production of Space (Blackwell, Oxford); first published 1974 Lefebvre H, 1993, `̀ The right to the city'', in Architecture Culture 1943 ^ 1968: A Documentary Anthology Ed. J Ockman (Rizzoli, New York) pp 428 ^ 436; first published 1968 Lefebvre H, 1996 Writings on Cities translated by E Kofman, E Lebas (Blackwell, Cambridge, MA) Lëgë B, 1995, `̀ Rëhabilitation et dësenclavement symbolique: la justice spatiale est-elle possible?'' [Rehabilitation or symbolic disenclavement: is social justice possible?] Les Annales de la recherche urbaine 68 ^ 69 34 ^ 42 Lelëvrier C, 1999, `̀ Renaissance or the end of urban policy?'' Les Cahiers de l'IAURIF 123 35 ^ 41 1804 M Dikec° Lenoir R,1974 Les exclus: un franc° ais sur dix [The excluded: one French out of ten] (Le Seuil, Paris) Leroux L, 2001, `̀A Marseille, les anciens de l'immigration, oubliës de la rënovation urbaine'' [In Marseille former immigrants left out of urban renovation] Le Monde 22 juin, page 11 Lojkine J, 1977 Le marxisme, l'ëtat et la question urbaine [Marxism, state and the urban question] (Presses Universitaires de France, Paris) Madanipour A,1998,`̀ Social exclusion and space'', in Social Exclusion in European Cities: Processes, Experiences, and Responses Eds A Madanipour, G Cars, J Allen (Jessica Kingsley, London) pp 75 ^ 89 Merrifield A, 1997, `̀ Social justice and communities of difference: a snapshot from Liverpool'', in The Urbanization of Injustice Eds A Merrifield, E Swyngedouw (New York University Press, New York) p 200 ^ 222 Merrifield A, Swyngedouw E, 1997, `̀ Social justice and the urban experience: an introduction'', in The Urbanization of Injustice Eds A Merrifield, E Swyngedouw (New York University Press, New York) pp 1 ^ 17 Miller D, 1976 Social Justice (Clarendon Press, Oxford) Mouffe C, 1992, `̀ Democratic citizenship and the political community'', in Dimensions of Radical Democracy: Pluralism, Citizenship, Community Ed. C Mouffe (Verso, London) pp 225 ^ 239 Perec G,1997 Speciesof Spaces and Other Pieces edited and translated by J Sturrock (Penguin Books, Harmondsworth, Middx); first published 1974 Pirie G H, 1983, `̀ On spatial justice'' Environment and Planning A 15 465 ^ 473 Rancie© re J, 1995, `̀ Politics, identification, and subjectivization'', in The Identity in Question Ed. J Rajchman (Routledge, London) pp 63 ^ 70 Rawls J, 1971 A Theory of Justice (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA) Rawls J, 1993 Political Liberalism (Columbia University Press, New York) Recherches 20,`̀ Loi d'orientation pour laville: sëminaire chercheurs dëcideurs'' [Urban development act: seminar with researchers and decisionmakers] Ministe© re de l'ëquipement, des transports et du logement (Paris, 1991) Sandel M J, 1982 Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge) Simon P, 1995, `̀ La politique de la ville contre la sëgrëgation: ou l'idëal d'une ville sans divisions'' [Urban policy against segregation: or the ideal of a city without divisions] Les Annales de la recherche urbaine 68 ^ 69 27 ^ 33 Skinner Q,1992,``On justice, the common good and the priority of liberty'', in Dimensions of Radical Democracy: Pluralism, Citizenship, Community Ed. C Mouffe (Verso, London) pp 211 ^ 224 Smith D M, 1994 Geography and Social Justice (Blackwell, Oxford) Smith D M, 1997, `̀ Back to the good life: towards an enlarged conception of social justice'' Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 15 19 ^ 35 Smith D M, 2000, `̀ Social justice revisited'' Environment and Planning A 32 1149 ^ 1162 Smith N, 1997, `̀ Social justice and the new American urbanism: the revanchist city'', in The Urbanization of Injustice Eds A Merrifield, E Swyngedouw (New York University Press, New York) pp 117 ^ 136 Soja E, 1989 Postmodern Geographies: The Reassertion of Space in Critical Social Theory (Verso, London) Soja E, 2000 Postmetropolis: Critical Studies of Cities and Regions (Blackwell, Oxford) Touraine A, 1991, `̀ Face a© l'exclusion'' Esprit 169 7 ^ 13 Voltaire, 1961 Mëlanges (Gallimard, Paris); first published 1761 Wihtol de Wenden C, 1992, `̀ Question de citoyennetë'' [The question of citizenship] Espaces et sociëtës 68 37 ^ 45 Young I M, 1990 Justice and the Politics of Difference (Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ) Young I M, 1999, `̀ Residential segregation and differentiated citizenship'' Citizenship Studies 3(2) 237 ^ 252 Justice and the spatial imagination 1805 ß 2001 a Pion publication printed in Great Britain Abstract Introduction Geographical encounters Urban sensibilities Spatial justice: a conceptualization Right to the city: beyond Conclusions: politicizing the urban spatial References work_jdxlgx4k7beyjca7ndi6nc6r6u ---- [PDF] Interactional justice, leader–member exchange, and employee performance: Examining the moderating role of justice differentiation | Semantic Scholar Skip to search formSkip to main content> Semantic Scholar's Logo Search Sign InCreate Free Account You are currently offline. Some features of the site may not work correctly. DOI:10.1002/JOB.2133 Corpus ID: 49535697Interactional justice, leader–member exchange, and employee performance: Examining the moderating role of justice differentiation @article{He2017InteractionalJL, title={Interactional justice, leader–member exchange, and employee performance: Examining the moderating role of justice differentiation}, author={W. He and R. Fehr and Kai Chi Yam and Lirong R. Long and P. Hao}, journal={Journal of Organizational Behavior}, year={2017}, volume={38}, pages={537-557} } W. He, R. Fehr, +2 authors P. Hao Published 2017 Psychology Journal of Organizational Behavior Summary Past research suggests that interactional justice plays a pivotal role in facilitating high-quality leader–member exchange (LMX), with downstream implications for employee performance. However, the broader context in which these effects unfold has received scarce attention. Drawing from deontic justice and social exchange theories, we suggest that interactional justice differentiation is an important contextual moderator of the link between interactional justice and LMX. Specifically… Expand View via Publisher static1.squarespace.com Save to Library Create Alert Cite Launch Research Feed Share This Paper 28 CitationsHighly Influential Citations 1 Background Citations 3 View All Figures and Tables from this paper figure 1 figure 2 table 2 table 3 figure 3 figure 4 View All 6 Figures & Tables 28 Citations Citation Type Citation Type All Types Cites Results Cites Methods Cites Background Has PDF Publication Type Author More Filters More Filters Filters Sort by Relevance Sort by Most Influenced Papers Sort by Citation Count Sort by Recency The influence of fair supervision on employees’ emotional exhaustion and turnover intentions Ivy A. Kyei-Poku Economics 2019 Save Alert Research Feed Unethical leader behavior and employee performance: a deontic justice perspective C. Gan, W. Guo, Yandong Chai, Duanxu Wang Economics 2019 2 Save Alert Research Feed Testing a Comprehensive Model of Organizational Justice Perceptions and Personal States with Personal and Organizational Outcomes Aharon Tziner, Erich C Fein, Cristinel Vasiliu Psychology 2020 PDF View 1 excerpt, cites background Save Alert Research Feed Why and When Empowering Leadership Has Different Effects on Employee Work Performance: The Pivotal Roles of Passion for Work and Role Breadth Self-Efficacy P. Hao, W. He, Lirong R. Long Psychology 2018 26 Save Alert Research Feed Beyond individual justice facets: How (Mis)alignment between justice climates affects customer satisfaction through frontline customer extra-role service behavior Michel Tremblay, Denis Chênevert, Christian Vandenberghe, Xavier Parent-Rocheleau Psychology 2018 4 Save Alert Research Feed Guanxi HRM practices and employee creative performance C. Yang, Fu Yang Psychology 2020 Save Alert Research Feed What make banks’ front-line staff more customer oriented? The role of interactional justice Thuy T. Dang, Anh D. Pham Business 2020 4 Save Alert Research Feed Transformational leadership, organizational justice and organizational outcomes: A study from the higher education sector in Syria Iyad Alamir, Rami M. Ayoubi, Hiba Massoud, Louna Al Hallak Psychology 2019 6 PDF Save Alert Research Feed Relationship between leader-member exchange and construction worker safety behavior: the mediating role of communication competence. Changquan He, Guangshe Jia, Brenda McCabe, J. Sun Psychology, Medicine International journal of occupational safety and ergonomics : JOSE 2019 5 Save Alert Research Feed An integrative ethical approach to leader favoritism Inju Yang, Sven Horak, Nada K. Kakabadse Psychology 2020 Save Alert Research Feed ... 1 2 3 ... References SHOWING 1-10 OF 93 REFERENCES SORT BYRelevance Most Influenced Papers Recency The impact of justice climate and justice orientation on work outcomes: a cross-level multifoci framework. H. Liao, D. Rupp Psychology, Medicine The Journal of applied psychology 2005 453 Highly Influential View 1 excerpt, references background Save Alert Research Feed The mediating roles of organizational justice on the relationships between HR practices and workplace outcomes: an investigation in China H. Zhang, Naresh C. Agarwal Psychology 2009 100 View 1 excerpt, references methods Save Alert Research Feed Using Social Exchange Theory to Distinguish Procedural from Interactional Justice R. Cropanzano, Cynthia A. Prehar, P. Chen Sociology 2002 752 View 3 excerpts, references background and results Save Alert Research Feed The precursors and products of justice climates: Group leader antecedents and employee attitudinal consequences. David M. Mayer, L. Nishii, B. Schneider, H. Goldstein Psychology 2007 192 PDF Save Alert Research Feed Collectivism as a moderator of responses to organizational justice: implications for leader‐member exchange and ingratiation B. Erdogan, R. Liden Psychology 2006 181 View 3 excerpts, references background and results Save Alert Research Feed What Is Wrong With Treating Followers Differently? The Basis of Leader–Member Exchange Differentiation Matters X. Chen, Wei He, Liang-Chieh Weng Psychology 2018 32 Save Alert Research Feed Employee Justice Across Cultures R. Shao, D. Rupp, D. Skarlicki, K. Jones Psychology 2013 150 Save Alert Research Feed Leader-Member Exchange and Employee Creativity: Test of a Multilevel Moderated Mediation Model W. Pan, Li-Yun Sun, I. H. Chow Psychology 2012 55 Save Alert Research Feed Justice at the millennium: a meta-analytic review of 25 years of organizational justice research. J. Colquitt, D. E. Conlon, M. J. Wesson, C. O. Porter, K. Ng Psychology, Medicine The Journal of applied psychology 2001 4,523 PDF View 1 excerpt, references background Save Alert Research Feed The Role of Justice in Organizations: A Meta-Analysis Yochi Cohen-Charash, P. Spector Psychology 2001 2,961 Save Alert Research Feed ... 1 2 3 4 5 ... Related Papers Abstract Figures and Tables 28 Citations 93 References Related Papers Stay Connected With Semantic Scholar Sign Up About Semantic Scholar Semantic Scholar is a free, AI-powered research tool for scientific literature, based at the Allen Institute for AI. Learn More → Resources DatasetsSupp.aiAPIOpen Corpus Organization About UsResearchPublishing PartnersData Partners   FAQContact Proudly built by AI2 with the help of our Collaborators Terms of Service•Privacy Policy The Allen Institute for AI By clicking accept or continuing to use the site, you agree to the terms outlined in our Privacy Policy, Terms of Service, and Dataset License ACCEPT & CONTINUE work_jgwvcgrnw5cdbdgqamslayk5mu ---- Zenodo_D51-KC- final-201130 The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 Co-designing Citizen Social Science for Collective Action #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building Environmental Justice This document is shared under Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (CC BY 4.0). Cite as: Arza, Valeria, Actis, Guillermina, Marchegiani, Pia, Velarde, Malena, Cane, Santiago, Buchsbaum, Malena & Swistun, Débora (2020). CoActD5.1: Report on Knowledge Coalition Building. Environmental Justice. Zenodo. http://doi.org/10.5281/zenodo.4498635 DISCLAIMER: The present Project Deliverable has been submitted to the European Commission for review. The information and views set out in this report are those of the author(s) and do not necessarily reflect the official opinion of the European Union. Neither the European Union institutions and bodies nor any person acting on their behalf may be held responsible for the use which may be made of the information contained therein. #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 2 Date – 30 November 2020 Dissemination level - Public Responsible Partner - UNSAM Author(s) / credits Arza, Valeria (CENIT/UNSAM): writing original draft, conceptualisation, methodology, investigation, formal analysis, supervision Actis, Guillermina (CENIT/UNSAM): writing original draft, conceptualisation, formal analysis, investigation. Marchegiani, Pia (FARN): writing review and editing, formal analysis, investigation and supervision Velarde, Malena (CENIT/UNSAM): writing review and editing, investigation, methodology, software, data curation, formal analysis, visualisation Cane, Santiago (FARN): formal analysis and investigation Buchsbaum, Malena (CENIT/UNSAM): writing review and editing, data curation, formal analysis Swistun, Débora (FARN): Investigation Reviewers - Isabelle Bonhoure, Teresa Wintersteller, Mariam Malik, Veronika Wöhrer, Katja Mayer Document History Version Date Contributor Comments 1.0 9th November 2020 Arza, V et al (lists of authors above) First draft KC report to be commented by Consortium coordinators. 2.0 17th November 2020 Arza, V et al Second draft after incorporating comments by UB. To be read by Consortium members. 3.0 26th November Arza, V et al Final draft of the report. #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 3 Table of Contents 1. Executive Summary 6 2. Introduction 7 2.1 CoAct General Concept 7 2.2 Definition of the Knowledge Coalition 8 2.3 R&I Action #3 Scope 9 3. Knowledge Coalition formation 12 3.1 Local context mapping 12 3.1.1 FARN Experience in Promoting Sanitation and Facilitating Citizen Participation in the Basin 12 3.1.2 CENIT/UNSAM Experience with Open Science and Citizen Participation in the Production of Knowledge Towards Transformation 16 3.1.4 Other Citizen Science Initiatives in the Riachuelo Basin 19 3.2 Knowledge Coalition constitution process 19 4. Knowledge Coalition in action 21 4.1 Knowledge Coalition Activities 22 4.1.1 Initiating First Contact: the Interviews 24 4.1.2 Micro-workshops, a tool to Co-produce Knowledge in Lockdown Time 25 4.1.3 Narrowing the Scope: Focussing on Strategic Topics 26 Participants 31 Methods - Dynamics 32 4.1.5 The Knowledge Coalition as a Network Approach 34 4.2 Knowledge Coalition Outcomes 37 4.2.1 Introduction 37 4.2.2 Socio-environmental Problems and Practices to address them 38 #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 4 4.2.3 The Meanings and Processes of Citizen Participation in Policy Making (for Community and Policy Actors) and on Knowledge Production (for Scientific Actors) 46 4.2.4 The First Steps Towards Platform Co-design 48 5. Concluding Remarks 49 6. References 53 #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 5 List of Figures Figure 1: Citizen Social Science in Action Figure 2: Network expansion in 18 months within and outside the Matanza-Riachuelo basin. Figure 3: Wordcloud of nouns for interviewees’ responses to the question on socio-environmental problems in the basin. Figure 4: Basin map and socio-environmental problems classified in six categories List of Tables Table 1: Technologies and main features of previous two versions of FARN’s QPR Table 2: Participants in different activities organised as part of CoAct R&I # 3 from April to October 2020 and digital tools used. Table 3: Selected Environmental Justice issues in Matanza-Riachuelo basin in connection to FARN´s agenda. List of Abbreviations ACUMAR: Matanza-Riachuelo Basin Authority CSS: Citizen Social Science CSOs: Civil Society Organisations GDPR: General Data Protection Regulation IC: Informed Consent PISA: Plan Integral de Saneamiento Ambiental (Sanitation Plan) QPR: Qué pasa Riachuelo? (What’s up Riachuelo) #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 6 1. Executive Summary CoAct (Co-designing Citizen Social Science for Collective Action) aims at co-designing concepts, methods and tools for Citizen Social Science around wicked global social issues. Four different research and innovation (R&I) actions organised the empirical work of CoAct and this report presents the process of building the knowledge coalition network for one of those R&I actions developed in the frame of CoAct WP5. This R&I action aims at co-designing citizen social science tools to facilitate actions contributing towards Environmental Justice in the Matanza-Riachuelo river basin. The basin covers 64 km-long and 6 million people live there, most of them in vulnerable socio-environmental situations. In particular, we aim at co-designing a digital platform to produce and share data that can contribute to mapping different socio-environmental problems as understood by a diversity of stakeholders and promote concrete actions for addressing those problems. The Knowledge Coalition works as a network of actors that intervene throughout the project’s R&I cycle, by discussing, defining, and co-designing different activities. We define it as the network of stakeholders who are interested in and informed about the R&I project goal and vision and who play an active role, either participating in or co-designing different actions. We expect the network to be continuously evolving and different types of commitment by a variety of actors is foreseen over time, depending on expertise, interests, synergies and project activities. FARN and CENIT/UNSAM identified three different types of actors that would be part of the Knowledge Coalition: researchers working in academic organisations doing research about different socio- environmental problems of the basin; public policy actors from the different jurisdictions involved in the basin (Municipal, Provincial and National) and community actors, which includes people living or working who belong to territorial organisations and also civil society organisations (CSOs) at large. #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 7 We had to modify our original plan for the Knowledge Coalition creation due to the Covid-19 pandemic and associated lockdown restrictions. We organised three types of virtual engagement activities with candidates to be part of the Knowledge Coalition: interviews, micro-workshops and a platform co-design workshop. In total we reached around 30 actors (research groups, public policy organisations and territorial and civil society organisations) inside and outside the basin, who participated in some of those instances and expressed their interest in being involved in the R&I action’s future activities. We managed to identify main socio-environmental problems in different locations in the basin as understood by different stakeholders who participated in our action. We also started to delineate the main purpose of the citizen driven platform, which will initially systematise and co-produce information on three main socio-environmental themes: conservation of green areas, water quality and relocation of people living in areas with environmental risks. 2. Introduction 2.1 CoAct General Concept CoAct (Co-designing Citizen Social Science for Collective Action) is proposing a new understanding of Citizen Social Science as a participatory research co-designed and directly driven by citizens and citizen groups sharing a social concern (See Figure 1). CoAct proposes to face four “wicked” social global issues by engaging citizens in a vulnerable situation. The approach represents a new understanding of the underexplored field of Citizen Social Science (CSS), understood here as participatory research co-designed with citizen groups sharing a social concern. The joint effort will result in the implementation of new or improved science-related policies and the advancement of the CSS approach with regards to its applicability in concrete fields or research. #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 8 Figure 1: Citizen Social Science in Action, with citizen groups, a specific concern, and with the support of the Knowledge Coalition In all CoAct R&I Actions (Mental Health Care, Youth Employment and Environmental Justice), citizens in a vulnerable situation are placed at the centre of the research and their role and dedication conceptually recognize them as Co-Researchers. In parallel, the Knowledge Coalition is a network of stakeholders who are informed about the R&I Actions’ goals, and play an active role, either participating in or co-designing different actions, to harness Co-Researchers' efforts and implement policies and measures based on scientific evidence. 2.2 Definition of the Knowledge Coalition Knowledge Coalitions are formed by representatives of Public Administrations, Civil Society Organisations (CSOs), educative organisations and Co-Researchers –to name a few. All R&I Actions involve people from different areas of the political, academic/scientific and social realm, according to their field of research. They strive to assure that the composition of the Knowledge Coalition reflects the diversity of actors within their field and is sensitive to gender balance and other socio-structural categories that might become relevant such as ethnicity or age. The involvement and collaboration of the Knowledge Coalition members varies according to the specific R&I Action and different actors may participate in different activities according to their expertise, interest and #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 9 expectations regarding synergies with their own activities associated to the social concern. The participation of the individual parties of the Knowledge Coalition can take place in various forms and in different moments of the R&I cycle: creating a structural framework for research, participating in the actual research process, informing on corresponding issues, implementing and discussing possible solutions or getting involved in the dissemination of the project and the transformation of research results into actions according to its acting potential. Regardless of the role, each R&I Action facilitates spaces for dialogue and action with different actors promoting the creation of a dynamic network and building from synergies among different initiatives adding therefore to the collective effort towards transformation. In order to coordinate the network and opening up spaces for deliberation, the R&I Actions use different methods and approaches, from joint discussions, workshops, expert talks and digital tools to strategy meetings, which aim at a diversity of on- and offline participation possibilities. 2.3 R&I Action #3 Scope The R&I Action on Environmental Justice explores socio-environmental problems in the Matanza- Riachuelo river basin with the aim of promoting transformative action. The Matanza-Riachuelo is a heavily contaminated 64 km long river that runs along the southern limit of the City of Buenos Aires, where 6 million people live. It is estimated that 1.8 million people in the basin live in highly vulnerable conditions1, in terms of housing and access to basic infrastructure. There are several socio-environmental problems related to: 1 See social vulnerability index build by ACUMAR (2018) p. 31 #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 10 i) contamination from production activities (mainly industrial but also agriculture); sewage effluents since 50% of population in the basin is not connected to sewage system (ACUMAR, 2020, p. 44) and open garbage dumps ii) poor infrastructure in terms of housing (around 800 people live in informal settlements and slums (ACUMAR, 2018, p.31), some of them built on garbage dumps), lack of access to safe water for 21 % of the basin population (ACUMAR, 2020, p.36), and poor access to health system, which exacerbate the social impact of contamination. The Knowledge Coalition works as a network of actors that intervene throughout the project’s R&I cycle, by discussing, defining, and co-designing the different steps towards constructing a digital platform to produce and share data that can contribute to the development and advancement of concrete actions or solutions for the basin’s problems. We will learn from the experience in designing and using a previous platform developed by FARN: QPR which stands for Qué pasa Riachuelo? (What’s up Riachuelo?). This platform will be re-built through co-design mechanisms incorporating different perspectives and viewpoints from the basin communities, scientists, and public authorities. The Citizen Science platform will produce knowledge and understandings about the nature of different socio-environmental problems starting from three of them: water quality, threats to green spaces such as wetlands, and the resettlement of families previously located in the basin towline path. By doing so, it aims to provide useful information to design potential solutions. FARN and CENIT/UNSAM will guide and implement a set of activities to co-create the Citizen Science platform and promote its dissemination: 1) open-ended interviews and workshops to identify socio-environmental problems in the Matanza-Riachuelo basin as they are understood by different actors as well as practices and activities aiming at addressing them; 2) co-design workshops, where #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 11 participants discuss the main functionalities and obstacles for the digital platform development and sustainability; 3) dissemination activities to generate new data sets on socio-environmental problems perception and to define how it can be contrasted with existing information sources and 4) open hackathons for data analysis, interpretation and visualisation of the results. The R&I Action on Environmental Justice’s main Knowledge Coalition actors, the Matanza-Riachuelo basin communities, scientists, and public bodies representatives, are identified through web-based research, bibliometric sources and FARN and CENIT/UNSAM previous connections. We have carried out three activities to reach these actors: interviews, micro-workshops and platform co-design workshops. During interviews, they narrate their experiences in the basin and their understanding of main problems and how citizen participation may help in the production of knowledge for transformative actions in the basin. Community actors also participate in micro- workshops designed to add bottom-up perspectives to social-environmental issues and identify key practices addressing them. Finally, socio-environmental problems identified through interviews and micro-workshops are discussed by the Matanza-Riachuelo communities’ actors, public bodies authorities, members from NGOs, and scientists in a platform co-design workshop. This context provides the opportunity to review preliminary outcomes on the identified problems from an enhanced perspective. The main goal of the co-design workshop is to have instances to reflect on the purpose, type of data and functionalities of the digital platform and to anticipate obstacles that may come up both when designing and using it. Workshops’ participants and interviewees who explicitly communicate their interest in being connected to projects activities and outcomes are all considered members of the Knowledge Coalition, which is then defined as a stakeholder network of actors interested in and informed about the R&I project goal and vision. This network includes activists, social and territorial organisations, NGO’s representatives, neighbours, scientists and policy makers mobilized to promote Environmental #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 12 Justice. The Knowledge Coalition contributes to frame both the R&I Action’s items goals and co- design different activities related to the Citizen Science platform. All actors in this network have experience in putting forward different activities aiming at providing knowledge and actions towards Environmental Justice. We plan to promote synergies with these actors’ practices. We foresee that, responding to their own interests in the different subject matter, actors in the Knowledge Coalition network will participate in and co-organise activities aiming at the design, dissemination, use and/or impact of the Citizen Science platform throughout the project. 3. Knowledge Coalition formation 3.1 Local context mapping The idea of creating a Citizen Science platform to address socio-environmental problems in Matanza-Riachuelo basin was first sketched in 2017. This project was inspired by FARN’s development of the citizen-driven data platform QPR and CENIT/UNSAM research experience on open science and citizen participation in the production of knowledge aiming at transformation. 3.1.1 FARN Experience in Promoting Sanitation and Facilitating Citizen Participation in the Basin In 2004 a group of local residents and workers from Villa Inflamable presented a lawsuit before the Supreme Court of Justice of the Nation (hereafter the Court). The lawsuit focused on environmental pollution damage in the Matanza-Riachuelo basin and a series of demands and claims against the National State, the Province of Buenos Aires, the Government of the City of Buenos Aires and forty- four companies. #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 13 In 2006 the Matanza-Riachuelo Basin Authority (ACUMAR) was created. ACUMAR is an autonomous public organisation which combines the work of the three levels of governments that have authority over the territory (National, Buenos Aires Province, and Buenos Aires City). It is the highest authority in the area on environmental issues. In 2008, the Court, in a landmark ruling, instructed ACUMAR: i) to repair air, water, and ground damage caused by discharges to the river; ii) to improve the quality of life of the citizens of the entire basin and iii) to prevent future damage. Also, in 2008 a group of Civil Society Organisations (CSOs), including FARN2 were admitted by the Court as third parties interested in the legal cause. Together with the Ombudsman, and other three CSOs, the Collegiate Body was created by the Supreme Court's ruling to monitor the environmental clean-up and the progress of the Sanitation Plan (PISA Plan Integral de Saneamiento Ambiental in Spanish). Specifically, among the given roles was to promote citizen participation in the monitoring of the environmental clean-up and associated activities of the basin. It was subsequently decided that this Collegiate Body assumes the actual representation of the public in that process of sanitation. The Court mandate was to foster citizen participation in the monitoring of ACUMAR´s work, especially in its compliance with the Sanitation Plan. In 2010 FARN and other CSOs initiated the project QPR Qué pasa Riachuelo? and in 2011 they launched the geo-referenced platform that enabled open access to data related to the ACUMAR’s PISA. The final expected outcome was that communities could monitor these activities’ execution and influence public policies in their territory. In a second stage, QPR published citizen-generated data, which was a very innovative move. QPR became one of the first citizen-driven platforms in the country. The new section, “Social Monitoring'', 2 The other CSOs were Greenpeace Argentina Foundation; Social and Legal Research Centre (Centro de Estudios Legales y Sociales) and Neighbours Association of La Boca. #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 14 established active mechanisms to control and watchdog the Sanitation Plan’s execution. This section included a new feature: a form that could be completed anonymously by citizens. This form gathered information that was then uploaded and published as a “story” (a neighbourhood alert taken by FARN to request further information on the matter to the competent authority) or as an “action” (an activity carried out by the community); whose responses were also published. “Social Monitoring'' section also included a “News” subsection that displayed a social survey on the presence of the issues associated with the Basin in the media. For more information on the case, please see Fressoli and Arza (2016) and Mira (2016). In its first stage of development, FARN and other CSOs established an agreement with ACUMAR to fetch data about PISA execution and to publish it on an interactive map. Neighbours from different parts of the basin and the CSOs involved were able to visualize this information and to contrast it with the cleaning up activities carried out in the basin’s territory. This was a key step since information was neither systematised nor easily accessible at that point in time. QPR 1 (2011) QPR 2 (2012-2014) Data Fetch data from ACUMAR. Display data on an interactive map. Fetch data from ACUMAR, TECHO. Publish data produced by social organisations. Display data on an interactive map. Citizen participation features Upload citizen-generated alerts using an online form administered during face-to-face workshops and meetings. Upload citizen-generated alerts using an online and public form. Platform provides environmental traffic light based on that data #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 15 Technologies USHAHIDI, JavaScript, CSS, HTML, ApacheConf Data cleansing Different instances of information cleansing: Collegiate body, FARN. Platform strategy development environment (Garage Lab). Citizen alerts and reports validated collectively during meetings. FARN staff checked citizen-generated data before publication. Data openness Datasets open to the public in csv format available on http://datospublicos.org/ Datasets open to the public in csv format. Dissemination activities Workshops at Matanza-Riachuelo basin schools. Workshops all along the Matanza- Riachuelo basin. Contact local newspapers. Table 1: Technologies and main features of previous two versions of FARN’s QPR Although FARN organised workshops and other activities within the community to foster platform use, spontaneous participation was rather low. First, neighbours from the basin did not perceive the platform as a tool to solve their problems and eventually lost interest in reporting any situation as there were no concrete responses carried-out by ACUMAR. Second, neighbours feared reprisals by powerful groups with conflicting interests (e.g., industries verting waste). Third, the wide digital and technology gap in the affected communities limited the platform’s use to the FARN workshops. The QPR’s dependency on workshops to feed its database weakened its community impact. As soon as the project ran out of funds to sustain the workshops, the generation of systematic information could not be further guaranteed. Funding was also needed for the cross-reference validation done by FARN’s own staff on the citizen information about breaches to existing regulation and on the follow-up with national authorities on the different issues raised on the platform. #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 16 Overall, QPR's main success was to push ACUMAR to grant access to information related to the Sanitation Plan, to systematize existing data and to make it visible. This was a central claim from communities seeking solutions to long-lasting socio environmental problems. In fact, ACUMAR ended-up developing its own geo-referenced tool showing information on socio-environmental basin’s problems, among other issues. However, the goal to foster citizen-generated data remained unfulfilled. The mentioned experiences made it clear that a new version of QPR had to be re-conceptualized to become a tool that could be uptaken by citizens. This goal not only aims at increasing the amount of citizen-generated data but also to build a sustainable platform that might become more independent from resources raised by leading organisations. 3.1.2 CENIT/UNSAM Experience with Open Science and Citizen Participation in the Production of Knowledge Towards Transformation In 2015 CENIT/UNSAM led a research project to understand how participatory science could contribute to overcoming health, inclusion, and environmental challenges in Argentina. This project was part of the Open and Collaborative Science in Development Network and CENIT/UNSAM research team analysed the Sanitary Camps (Campamentos Sanitarios) in different rural and peri urban settings. These camps were organised by medical faculty and students responding to communities’ demand for epidemiological data in locations exposed to pesticide sprayings. The Sanitary Camps were held from 2010 until 2019 as part of the medical curricula at the National University of Rosario School of Medicine and produced epidemiological data representing more than 100,000 people (Verzeñassi & Vallini, 2019). The camps involved communities and local governments in the research process and the dissemination of the collected data. Their action had a tremendous political and social impact, especially for Sprayed Peoples (Pueblos Fumigados) and #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 17 other socio-environmental movements that tried to document the detrimental human health impacts of the agro-industrial system based on extensive use of pesticides, a research area barely studied. Eventually, the Sanitary Camps were dismantled by the School of Medicine’s authorities. A great opportunity for transformation was lost and the question on how participatory science aiming at transformation in a political conflictive situation could overcome social, cultural and political barriers remains open. These are typical obstacles in undone science (Hess, 2007) and studying them is particularly critical for open science scholars as we struggle with the question of how to incorporate political angle when dealing with methodological decisions, such as how to share data and information without risk of data being misused or the projects being boycotted/suppressed. When researchers from CENIT/UNSAM first learnt about QPR, they got very enthusiastic about the role the tool had in pushing public policy forward. They also saw the potential to go beyond its social monitoring role and to use it to create relevant knowledge for solving pressing socio-environmental problems, influencing public policy and promoting transformative actions. As the Sanitary Camps experience showed, when the community gets involved in participatory research, they do so mobilised by the urge to change their reality. The community could tell what types of practices could work better than others. Social scientists and CSOs could also contribute methodologically and by promoting strategic alliances to push data and ideas to convert into public policy and actions. CENIT/UNSAM has been very active in advocating open science policies in Argentina. The research centre has actively collaborated with other research organisations, CSOs and public policy, including the Science and Technology Policy authority to advance discussions on both the promotion of open and citizen science and how to articulate it into public policy schemes. Activities included seminars, policy workshops, technical assistance, festivals, community workshops and other dissemination activities. All these activities allowed CENIT/UNSAM to better understand the potential #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 18 challenges in developing citizen science projects, addressing also the necessary alliances for conducting this type of research. 3.1.3 CoAct Riachuelo In 2017 both teams started to collaborate and jointly developed the vision that citizen participation facilitated by digital tools could promote transformative actions towards Environmental Justice in the basin. They agreed to learn from QPR experience and re-launch a new platform to share and create new knowledge on citizen’s understanding of socio-environmental problems and their practical experiences in dealing with them. Based on their previous experience and connections, FARN and CENIT/UNSAM defined that there were three types of actors that had to be involved to put forward their project on Citizen Science for Environmental Justice. First, CSOs that had been participating in the basin's judicial conflict and the public policy catalysed by it and territorial organisations or individuals from the community with personal experience in searching for solutions to socio- environmental problems to be prioritized (see below). FARN is the primary contact point for their previous experience working with these local groups or organisations. We aim at good gender and geographical balance. Second, academic organisations and researchers working on those socio-environmental issues or with experience in advancing Citizen Science projects. CENIT/UNSAM is the main contact point, and selection considers disciplinary and gender diversity, with a particular focus on Universities located in the basin and research groups with previous experience in participatory science. Third, policy makers from different jurisdictional levels (municipalities, provincial and national) with presence in different geographical areas of the basin, with special focus and responsibilities on environmental or sanitation policies. FARN and CENIT/UNSAM would work side by side to bring along these stakeholders, building from their previous networks and expertise. #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 19 3.1.4 Other Citizen Science Initiatives in the Riachuelo Basin We must also mention some particular experiences of Citizen Science in the Matanza-Riachuelo basin, associated with socio-environmental problems, which are close cousins of our R&I action and whose main representatives are also part of our Knowledge Coalition. On the one hand, AppEAR is a project with both scientific and educational goals, that aims at mapping aquatic habitats of the continental water bodies in Argentina. It also includes educational content and games in a mobile application and web-based platform (Cochero, 2018). The basin’s territory is included in the more 400 sampling sites of the project. Anticipando la Crecida was launched in 2014 as an extension project from the University of Buenos Aires. Since 2017 it has an agreement with Municipality of La Matanza, one of the jurisdictions that is more affected by the risk parameters identified by ACUMAR (ACUMAR, 2018). Biodiversity in the Matanza-Riachuelo basin (Biodiversidad de La Cuenca Matanza-Riachuelo · INaturalist, n.d.) is a Citizen Science initiative promoted by FARN in the context of the international program “Humedales sin Fronteras” (Wetlands without borders). The initiative uses the platform iNaturalist to register citizens observations of natural species in the area, promoting their conservation and the visibility of the threats that affect them. 3.2 Knowledge Coalition constitution process Once we identified the three different groups—policy makers, science actors and community actors—we started mapping potential candidates within each of them. FARN included community members who were known to be active in the basin, based on their own experience and also drawing from existing networks of territorial organisations and other CSOs working with them. CENIT/UNSAM searched for academic actors by analysing public bibliometric databases as well as the national portal on information in science and technology, which includes projects, researchers and scientific database. The list of candidates of policy actors include all relevant organisations working on environmental and sanitation policy in the basin. From these lists CENIT/UNSAM and FARN #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 20 collectively selected 45 people (50% female) as potential candidates to be invited to the project activities and who therefore could become part of the Knowledge Coalition. We sought to promote diversity in terms of variables mentioned above: gender, geography, political jurisdiction and discipline. In addition, especially in the case of community and policy actors, previous connection was also a variable that weighed heavily in our selection decision. Before formally contacting any of these actors, we worked on the ethical and data security aspects of these activities. This proved to be challenging since there is not much experience in ethical procedures for social sciences in Argentina. Neither UNSAM nor FARN had an Ethical Committee who could revise our procedures. We reviewed several informed consent (IC) procedures for other research areas, and we studied Argentinean regulation both on Personal Data and science and technology activities, which are both consistent with General Data Protection Regulation (GDPR). Our research activities are aligned with the ethics requirements contemplated in the 3º article of the Argentinian Law 25.467 of the National System of Science, Technology and Innovation, regarding the inalienable and universal principles for conducting research activities. Additionally, the project is compliant with the Law 25.326 of personal data protection requisites, as the investigation procedures contemplate informing the participants about how their personal data will be handled and processed. For this purpose, IC forms have been developed, in order to make participants aware of their rights and of the data's different uses. The procedure was approved by the UNSAM Vice Dean office, which is responsible for research projects in UNSAM. We developed different IC forms for the different planned activities; these were later modified, to adapt to the online activities as imposed by the Covid-19’s lockdown measures. Eventually we also simplified them using plain language techniques and video formats to address certain obstacles (see more on section 4.1 below). The IC forms and procedures for our R&I action also benefited widely from contributions by other researchers in the CoAct consortium. #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 21 Finally, regarding Data Protection, we discussed our research data cycle for the development of the data management plan by Open Knowledge Foundation, part of CoAct consortium. When our research activities started and we began to generate and collect data we consulted with the UNSAM information technology team on cybersecurity issues in the context of home office imposed by the lockdown. They informed us to continue working with the institutional accounts of the cloud service of GDrive provided by the UNSAM. We have also requested remote access to the institution’s service to make monthly backups. 4. Knowledge Coalition in action Our plans to build the Knowledge Coalition had to be modified due to the Covid-19 pandemic and associated lockdown measures that started in mid-March 2020 and continue until the present time (early November 2020). People need special permits to move further than 500 meters away from home and gathering indoors is forbidden. Thus, our planned activities had to go fully virtual and it became challenging to reach both community actors —who had poor or no connectivity— and policy makers. Our research takes place in the areas more heavily affected by the Covid-19 spread. In addition, Argentina is going through an economic crisis, which preceded the lockdown but has worsened by the pandemic and associated lockdown measures. Therefore, both community and policy makers are affected by high degrees of sanitarian and economic urgencies. To build the Knowledge Coalition we planned to perform interviews from the above-mentioned list of 45 people, and to organise a “recognition workshop” to consolidate it, and jointly co-design the upcoming activities. The workshop was planned for the first semester of 2020 and was first postponed under the expectations that restrictions were going to end within a few months. As this did not happen, we eventually had to cancel the face-to-face format. We proceeded to interview #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 22 potential Knowledge Coalition actors and replaced the “recognition workshop” with other types of virtual workshops as discussed in more detail below. 4.1 Knowledge Coalition Activities For developing the network of actors to be part of the Knowledge Coalition we developed three different types of activities: interviews, micro-workshops with the community, and a platform co- design workshop. Table 2 briefly summarises the characteristics of participants and the digital tools used in each instance, which are described in more detail below. #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building | The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 23 Date Platforms used Science actors Public policy actors Community actors Total participants Territorial organisations from the Basin NGOs or other CSOs People Organisations / projects Micro- Workshop 1 participants 11/8/2020 Zoom People - - 6 2 8 2 (Organisations) (1) (1) Micro- Workshop 2 participants 25/8/2020 Zoom People - - 6 2 8 4 (Organisations) (3) (1) Interviewees April to September 2020 Zoom/Meet People 11 5 1 4 21 17 (Organisations. / research groups) (9) (4) (1) (3) Workshop participants 29/10/2020 Zoom/ Jamboard/ Mentimeter/ Padlet People 2 9 4 7 22 17 (Organisations. / research groups) (2) (6) (3) (6) Actors in the Knowledge Coalition network (counted only once, although they may have participated in different activities) 51 30 Table 2: Participants in different activities organised as part of CoAct R&I # 3 from April to October 2020 and digital tools used #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 24 4.1.1 Initiating First Contact: the Interviews We designed three types of questionnaires for one-hour interviews with the three different types of actors. The questionnaire includes some questions that were common to all types of actors and some actor-type’s specific ones. Among the former, we ask about the role/experience/activities of each actor in the basin; the problems/issues that each actor understands as the most relevant and the best/possible solutions that they identify. In addition, we asked all of them about the role of citizen participation in policy making (for community and policy actors) and on knowledge production (for academic actors). Finally, we also ask them to recommend some other groups or projects that may be interested in our project, so as to continue enlarging our network. Regarding the specific sections, for community actors, there were questions regarding the role of public policies; for academic actors, there were questions about the contribution of science in policy making; and, finally, for policy makers we asked about their priorities in the basin and how they matched those coming from community actors. We performed 18 interviews, some of them to individual actors and others, to a couple of them jointly. As can be seen in Table 2, there were 5 people from the community or CSOs, 11 from the scientific organisations and 5 from the policy sector; 57% of them were women. In all interviews IC forms were sent in advance, 30% provided oral consent during the interviews. Most interviews were recorded. IC for interviews included a series of statements for which people could choose their preference regarding the use of personal data. In general, people have agreed on us sharing direct quotes from interviews and attributing them with full names, but they normally requested us to show quotes beforehand. Particularly for community actors, IC procedures resulted to be cumbersome. Some of the expressed obstacles were associated with the provision of digital signatures and with the length and technical language. To address these, we opted for oral consents #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 25 in some cases and eventually simplifying the content and changing the procedure for community members (see below). 4.1.2 Micro-workshops, a tool to Co-produce Knowledge in Lockdown Time During July and August, we organised online micro-workshops to be held only with members of the basin’s local communities. The purpose of these workshops was to collect these stakeholders’ collective views on socio-environmental problems and their practices to overcome them. They were planned together with Iconoclasistas, the art-group that is also part of our Knowledge Coalition, who are the experts in the collective mapping methodologies that were part of the activities we had planned for our R&I action pre-Covid-19. So far micro-workshops have been organised with participants from two different locations of the basin. There were six participants in each workshop, who knew each other and lived nearby and belong to territorial organisations such as museums, schools, and neighbour associations. Workshops were coordinated through WhatsApp groups to agree on schedule, to share information, including IC materials and to answer specific questions. They were conducted through video calls in the Zoom platform. They were only audio-recorded. During the workshops, Iconoclasistas worked with maps of the neighbourhoods and asked participants to use a piece of paper, which was divided in three columns. In each of them they had to identify problems, positive practices to address them, and most prominent territorial organisations responsible for those practices. They were also asked to geo-reference those elements. Micro- workshops lasted over two hours and a half, during which people shared their annotations and thoughts while Iconoclasistas were taking notes on the maps. People interacted while presenting their views, complementing their experiences and getting involved in conversations about problems, practices, actors and locations. #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 26 The micro-workshop method was an adequate approach for producing rich information and could work as a first step in the process of co-designing a Citizen Social Science project in a digital environment: it allowed to engage the communities in a discussion with researchers in a dynamic way, because it generated a sense of collective belonging. Through the dialogue it allowed the development of a collective vision of socio-environmental problems. Since the method contributes to the identification of actors and practices that help to solve problems, it facilitates the discussion about future possible pathways for action. This information was very rich for expanding the map of actors and also for identifying positive practices. Based on our experience with IC forms in interviews with community actors, for micro-workshops we decided to change our IC procedures. FARN produced a video which explains the main activities of our R&I action, including how the information was going to be used. The video and a statement on our commitment regarding the use of the data was sent by WhatsApp, and participants had the chance to ask questions using the same platform. In addition, we dedicated the first half an hour to read a plain language version of the aspects that required consent, showed the video again, answered any question and recorded an oral statement of agreement from all participants. 4.1.3 Narrowing the Scope: Focussing on Strategic Topics Based on the information gathered during interviews and considering FARN's experience and agenda in the basin, we decided to start working on three issues, all of which are of great relevance in relation to Environmental Justice and citizen participation. Those issues are water quality; protection of green areas and relocation of population affected by situations of environmental risk. The decision to focus on these issues was both strategic and practical. On the one hand, FARN has been leading both judicial activities and territorial engagement on these topics, and thus it makes #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 27 sense to focus the development of the platform on issues well connected to FARN’s current and future agenda. On the other hand, given lockdown restrictions, and because we were not able to organise collective mapping workshops as initially planned, we decided to start working in the platform’s co-design using virtual on-line workshops. To make them manageable, we needed to reduce the quantity of socio-environmental issues and thus, decided to start working on the topics that were identified —in interviews and micro workshops— as relevant and coincide with FARN’s own agenda. The platform could then incorporate other socio-environmental demands. Water quality is a key issue in the Riachuelo basin. The water receives sewage and industrial effluents, as well as solid urban waste, which represent the main causes of contamination in the basin. By jointly analysing the water quality and the evolution of associated regulation, it is possible to observe both the advances or setbacks in polluting factors and in public policies aimed at rebuilding the environment and preventing future damage. ACUMAR has the leading role in terms of ruling about water quality. The Collegiate Body is currently demanding the setup of new limits in terms of permitted discharge amounts and water quality goals that may allow the restoration of the river. In 2017 new regulation was issued which modifies parameters but expected improvements in terms of water quality based on those new values and assessment methods are marginally. The water quality goal that has been established, according to the Collegiate Body, is also insufficient to reduce contamination. By including this topic on the platform, the population could report isolated events, such as strange spills, increased rubbish in the water mirror. Also, they could share their understanding or personal experience on water quality or public policy, and how that matters for their lives. For several years, FARN brought evidence on these issues, partly collected using the preliminary versions of QPR as a #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 28 social monitoring tool3. The organisation systematically discussed in Court the importance of water quality, since it is a central issue for environmental recompositing. The wetlands of the basin are the most significant green spaces, the sites with the greatest biodiversity in the basin, where nature becomes present in an urban setting. This issue has been prioritized because it accounts for the relation between people and ecosystems, their involvement in taking care and valuing the last remaining natural areas within a highly dense metropolitan region. The state of wetlands is highly relevant for basin environmental health. They provide fundamental environmental services and constitute the main tool for environmental re-composition since the river has minimal slope, with almost stagnant waters. Nevertheless, wetlands in the basin are territories under dispute, with several different actors pushing for their access to land. Citizens groups have collectively requested the legal protection of these areas for a long time. Some protection was achieved in some areas of the basin. However, both real estate companies and different private projects (including a waste management company) have occupied these areas, putting them in danger. There are different kinds of conflicts in the area, involving not only different jurisdictions but also diverse economic, habitational and nature conservation interests. Many of these conflicts are taken to the judiciary powers. 3 The regulation of water quality and its control have been highlighted by the Collegiate Body in the last hearings convened by the Supreme Court in 2016 and 2018, as can be seen in the public access file (Autos “Mendoza, Beatriz y otros c/ Estado Nacional y otros s/ daños y perjuicios (daños derivados de la contaminación ambiental del Río Matanza Riachuelo)”, expte. Nº CSJN 1569/04(40-M)) and especially in presentations “Opinión del Cuerpo Colegiado 2016” and “Resumen de la presentación - Cuerpo Colegiado - Audiencia 14-3-18”. Also in the published document “9 años del fallo de la Corte. Una política de Estado todavía ausente. 2017”. On the other hand, in the execution file of the sentence in relation to water quality (“Acumar c/ Estado de Aguas, napas subterráneas y calidad de aire” FSM 052000003/2013, that processes before Juzgado Federal de Morón Nº2) there are numerous presentations by the Collegiate Body in relation to Resolution 46/17 on water quality. #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 29 Moreover, a draft law on the protection of wetlands is being discussed at the national level in Congress, which could have a high impact on the Riachuelo Basin. FARN has been working on protecting wetlands for several years4. The organisation has advocated for wetlands to become natural reserves, using different legal strategies including litigation. Hence, it has strong ties with territorial organisations and residents who work for their protection. Some are members of the Knowledge Coalition and co-researchers in this R&I action. FARN is currently part of a campaign to achieve the legal protection of Ciudad Evita´s wetland and also monitors the situation of other wetlands, making legal presentations as to avoid alterations to those ecosystems. Finally, we included relocation of the population5 living in areas with environmental risks for three reasons. Firstly, this is a question of great social and legal relevance: as part of the judicial mandate of the Supremes Court, around 17,700 families had to forcibly move in order to restore the 4 Through its biodiversity area, FARN has been working on the protection of wetlands for several years, throughout the national territory and particularly in the Matanza Riachuelo Basin. FARN promotes the enactment of a wetland protection law (https://farn.org.ar/leydehumedalesya-ambientalistas-piden-avanzar-con-un-texto-unificado/) and works for the specific protection of wetlands in the Riachuelo through studies (https://farn.org.ar/wp- content/uploads/2020/10/Reserva-Ciudad-Evita.pdf), written and audio-visual publications (https://youtu.be/- gN7A2o0Arw https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=_pMRW2Lihto&feature=youtu.be https://farn.org.ar/preocupacion- por-la-reserva-municipal-santa-catalina/),presentations to administrative authorities (https://farn.org.ar/alerta-en- santa-catalina-por-obras-de-ampliacon-de-vias/ https://farn.org.ar/farn-pidio-al-poder-ejecutivo-de-la-provincia-de- buenos-aires-vetar-la-ley-que-desafecta-64-hectareas-de-la-reserva-natural-laguna-de-rocha/ ) and before the court of execution of the sentence "Mendoza", where various intrusions in the wetlands of the basin have been denounced and the judge was able to order the creation of an environmental evaluation system in ACUMAR of works and projects to be carried out in wetlands or protected natural areas and to protect (all this can be seen in the public access file “Ordenamiento territorial (autorización de mov. de suelos) s Contencioso” FSM 052000017/2013, that processes before Juzgado Federal de Morón Nº2). 5 Part of the actions that FARN has developed in this matter can be reflected in the hearings cited in note 1 and in the file of relocations of the execution of the sentence “Mendoza” (“Acumar s/ Urbanización de villas y asentamientos precarios s/ Contencioso Administrativo”FSM 052000001/2013, that processes before Juzgado Federal de Morón Nº2). There, irregularities have been reported in construction projects, shortcomings in moving processes and lack of compliance by political leaders. The organisation also participated in a public hearing held to create a relocation protocol (https://www.acumar.gob.ar/wp-content/uploads/2016/12/Informe-Final-Audiencia-P%C3%BAblica-2017.pdf ). #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 30 environment and avoid risks to the population. New houses have been slowly built (over 4000). There have been discussions about the quality of the new houses, their location (in relation to the life plan of the people and the environmental status of the new locations), the quality of the constructions, the participation of the people affected in the processes and decision-making. As a matter of fact, this is the only issue included in the judicial cause that had direct participation of affected people. There are many different ways in which policy making has responded to these processes. But the information is dispersed; each process has been carried out without information from the others. The platform could then be a very relevant tool to facilitate participation, to share experiences and practical knowledge, and to strengthen connections that may enable transformative actions towards improving living conditions for communities in the basin. Issue Relevance Connection to FARN’s agenda Platform´s potential contribution (examples) water quality Sewage and industrial effluents, as well as solid urban waste, represent the main causes of contamination in the basin. For several years, FARN brought evidence on water quality. The organisation systematically discussed its importance in Court. To share people understanding or personal experience on water quality or public policy, and how that matters for their lives. protection of green areas Green areas provide fundamental environmental services and constitute the main tool for environmental re-composition. Nevertheless, wetlands in the basin are territories under dispute, with several different actors pushing for their access to land. FARN has been working on protecting wetlands for several years. The organisation has advocated for wetlands to become natural reserves, using different legal strategies including litigation. Articulation among different organisations, for instance to share strategies towards green area conservation. relocation of population affected by situations of environmental risk As part of the judicial mandate of the Supremes Court, around 17,700 families had to forcibly move in order to restore the environment and avoid risks to the population. There FARN has been active in reporting irregularities in relation to relocations in different judicial causes. The organisation also participated in public hearings held to create a relocation protocol To share experiences and practical knowledge, and to strengthen connections that may enable transformative actions towards improving living conditions for communities #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 31 have been discussions about the quality of the new houses, their location (in relation to the life plan of the people and the environmental status of the new locations), the quality of the constructions, the participation of the people affected in the processes and decision-making. in the basin. Table 3: Selected Environmental Justice issues in Matanza-Riachuelo to start working in the platform co- design 4.1.4 Targeting the Platform: the Co-design Workshop The goal of the workshop was to produce a first brainstorming of ideas about how the platform could become a useful tool for sharing ideas, experiences and practices in relation to problems and solutions involved in each of the three selected topics. At the same time, this workshop enabled the interaction among members of our Knowledge Coalition network for the first time. Therefore, it had the double purpose of formally launching the project and creating a space for the stakeholders to start interacting. We needed a virtual space designed for people to share their ideas regarding the project’s purpose, in the context of lockdown restrictions, this had to be virtual. We adapted methods for a digital experience taking into consideration that it included people who were not necessarily accustomed to digital tools, neither they knew each other. Participants We built a list of 120 potential candidates to be invited to the workshop. Among them there were 15% from scientific organisations, 33% from policy and 52% from the community. The invitations included a flyer for advertising the event, the workshop programme and a registration form which #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 32 included the video on information of personal data management (same video as in micro-workshops). To register for the workshop, people had to agree on our data policy, and they could opt for their names to be mentioned as participants. Only those properly registered were contacted with the virtual credential to attend the meeting. Especially among community members, there were some people that were not included in the original list but learned about the workshops by other members of the community and asked for permission to participate, which was granted in all cases. Members of CENIT/UNSAM and FARN pursued a dedicated follow-up of invitees. In total there were 34 registered participants and over half of them actually participated in the workshop. Among participants, there were around 10% from scientific organisations, 45% from community and CSOs and 45% from Policy covering different jurisdictions; 50% of participants were female and their interests were evenly spread around the three thematic areas. Some people that had registered to participate afterwards explained that they had overlapping activities but were still interested in the project. Also, at the last moment some community members who had registered to participate had to deal with some emergency situation in their territory and did not attend. We will follow-up on this too. Methods - Dynamics The workshop lasted two hours and included plenary and group sessions. The main goal of the activity was to gather information on the participants’ inputs on the project main outcome: an open- source Citizen Science platform for promoting actions towards Environmental Justice There were three plenary sessions, with group sessions in-between. We used several digital tools as mentioned below and enabled the Zoom chat for conversation and reactions. The first plenary included presentations by representatives of both leading organisations (FARN and CENIT/UNSAM) about the project and its Citizen Social Science approach. After these, a collective #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 33 exercise to gather information was conducted using the online tool of wordcloud of Mentimeter. Two questions were posed to the group in order to understand participants' perception of the existing problems: first, we presented a question on the main socio-environmental problems in the basin; and second, we proceeded similarly but focussing on of each the three topics of interest: conservation of green areas, water quality and relocations. The wordclouds that emerged from this session were then used as inputs for the discussions on both group sessions. The second plenary session consisted of a brief presentation of FARN’s previous versions of QPR platform and their interest in promoting the participation in the basin as a fundamental aspect of Environmental Justice. The relevance of the three thematic areas was also briefly discussed. Finally, the last plenary session included the presentation of the group discussions and a reflexive exercise conducted by ZSI to gather information on the participants’ expectations about the project using the Padlet tool. The group discussions were facilitated and annotated by CENIT/UNSAM and FARN teams. The first group session aimed at identifying how people got informed about socio-environmental problems in the basin with the idea to create an initial map of the type and sources of information about the basin that could be included in the platform. Therefore, we used the first group session as a first anchor in the process of collectively discussing the project: stakeholders were asked about their knowledge regarding information sources and formats and the problems they face when using it. This contributed to focus on the project’s main goal (to create an online Citizen Science platform to map socio-environmental problems and potential solutions) by broadening out the diversity of perspectives of what is considered useful information. The second session was more directly associated with the project’s expected output: we asked participants to discuss their ideas about the platform’s purpose and the information to be produced and shared through it on each thematic topic. We used the wordclouds from the mentimeter exercise as reflexive points but with the focus on online interactive formats (as presented by the examples #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 34 from the first session). We also asked about obstacles and problems that may turn up when designing and using such a platform. The group sessions were organised through breakout rooms where the facilitators used the Google Jamboard tool to introduce the discussions in interactive ways, and for the participants to be able to write their thoughts and opinions in a more direct way, considering they may not feel initially comfortable with sharing them out loud. The boards also aimed at providing a record of the discussions, and to allow the facilitators to have inputs to catalyse the conversation, as they were shared online and the annotations visible for the participants in the other breakout rooms, allowing for cross fertilization of the debate. 4.1.5 The Knowledge Coalition as a Network Approach We initiated the project idea in close collaboration with a dozen of actors among policy makers, CSOs and community actors, and researchers from academic organisations, all of whom wrote letters of support for the project proposal in March 2019. In Figure 2 we draw how the network expanded both outside but especially inside the Matanza-Riachuelo basin. New actors who shared the R&I action were contacted by FARN and CENIT/UNSAM to take part in some of the activities we described above. There were also some few cases that initiated the contact themselves. Those that expressed their interest to remain connected are considered part of the Knowledge Coalition network, reaching a total of 32 actors, classified in research groups (28%), public policy organisations (22%) and CSOs (50%).6 6 In Table 2 we stated that there 29 unique organisations which participated in the R&I action activities but in Figure 2 there are two additional organizations (one NGO and one territorial organization) which are part of our knowledge coalition since 2019. #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 35 Thus, we define our Knowledge Coalition as a network of stakeholders who are interested in and informed about the R&I project goal and vision and who play an active role, either participating in or co-designing different actions. Actors in this network interact and deliberate in spaces mainly facilitated by the project's coordination team. In all cases, we seek to build from synergies of their activities in the basin. 36 Figure 2: Network expansion in 18 months within and outside the Matanza-Riachuelo basin #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 37 4.2 Knowledge Coalition Outcomes 4.2.1 Introduction This section is organised in three blocks. First, based on interviews and micro-workshops, we present the socio-environmental problems and actors’ socio-technical practices addressing them. We found an extensive list of socio-environmental problems affecting the basin that we classified in broad categories, developed to allow comparability with other sources of information, especially ACUMAR. We contrast these understandings across different types of actors and in different locations. Second, we focus on the concept of participation for the production of knowledge that could contribute towards transformation. We are interested in reflecting from the perspective of different actors conforming the Knowledge Xoalition their understandings on the value of participation and also on how participation could be implemented and supported. We believe it is important to recognize that there are different ways in which participants could engage with Citizen Science projects (Haklay, 2018), depending on their interests, capabilities and project goals. Thus, in our R&I action we also expect that participation will adopt different characteristics for different actors in different activities and processes. Particularly, we are interested in addressing how the communities, in general, and co-researchers who are part of the Knowledge Coalition will participate. In this section we will present an approach to the stakeholders’ perceptions of citizens’ participation in both policymaking and knowledge production processes. These inputs are key to better understand the expectations and tensions that may appear when co-designing the project and defining its focus in the different instances with the knowledge coalition members #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 38 Third, we present preliminary results on the co-design workshop, particularly in relation to the participating stakeholders’ experience in using available information about the basin and their ideas on the purpose and potential obstacles in using the platform. 4.2.2 Socio-environmental Problems and Practices to address them Figure 37 depicts the most important issues raised by different actors when asked, in an interview setting, about socio environmental problems. 7 This wordcloud displays the frequency of nouns used by interviewees to answer the question “What are the Matanza- Riachuelo basin’s main socio-environmental problems?”. We used the bag-of-words method coded in Python to represent the multiset of the words used in this part of the interview and then we filtered all terms that did not match the noun criteria. Finally, we rendered the resulting dataset using nubedepalabras.es #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 39 Figure 3: Wordcloud of nouns for interviewees’ responses to the question on socio-environmental problems in the basin Those words come as responses to the specific section in the questionnaire asking about socio- environmental problems. Thus, issues related to the water, sanitation, floods, sewage system, settlements (informal housing), rubbish, contamination and health stand out in the wordcloud. However, there are also other nouns, which do not represent problems, specifically, but relate to the situated experience of actors in the basin: such as river, neighbourhoods, neighbours, water streams, territory, work, people, etc. The interviews’ and micro-workshops’ materials (transcriptions and notes) were analysed to map the main issues of the basin identified by the stakeholders. After listing these problems, we codified them into six categories that emerged from the project's original proposal and could work to contrast our findings with official public policy’s documents. The six categories of problems are the following: #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 40 • social vulnerability: includes any reference from the interviewees or micro-workshops’ participants to the conditions affecting the living standards of communities in the basin. These conditions include infrastructure deficiencies related to the provision of public services and basic rights such as access to food, health, education and housing as well as references to the stigma that such conditions may produce. • contamination: the material consequences of different activities that affect the basin’s environment related to productive activities, deficient public infrastructure and/or individual behaviour. • green spaces conservation: actions and situations that refer to the disturbance of public areas that provide environmental and recreational services to the basin. Some of them were legally defined as objects of protection. • flooding: references to the events produced by the covering or submerging of normally dry land by heavy precipitations and river overflow. • health problems: all the individual or collective discomforts or diseases that actors directly associate with living in the basin or with contamination. • public policy (actions and inactions): the issues identified as part of the actions or absence of them that are meant to be implemented by the public policy authorities (national, provincial or local) to comply with the judicial sentence request, and translated into the PISA. These categories have some relation with the ones contemplated by ACUMAR’s risk maps, develop to determine the prioritization of the different policy interventions8. The authority refers to social 8 In 2018 the authority developed an environmental risk map (ACUMAR, 2018) with the purpose of guiding public policy interventions (mainly relocations/urbanizations and infrastructure) and a health risk map (Pasqualini et al., 2018) that incorporates among other variables the Integral Evaluations of Environmental Health in Risk Areas (EISAAR for their initials #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 41 vulnerability—defined as the ascertainable condition of certain groups associated with their exposition to socioeconomic, habitational, sanitary, nutritional, psychosocial and environmental factors that determine their capacity to recover from catastrophes and threats—when including as a variable the people’s housing conditions (for which there is available consolidated official data). Floods and contamination are reflected as several of the threats that are determinants of risk: landfills (sites identified and tracked by the Direction of Solid Waste Management), presence of industrial establishments (considered as priority for control as these industries have been categorized as high in environmental complexity) and the quality of the underground water for human consumption (evaluating the presence of nitrates, as an indicator of potential contamination by industrial activities). The health index considers several issues associated with the morbidity and mortality produced by environmental diseases and contamination (as evaluated by ACUMAR in air, water, land, etc.). Finally, protected areas and wetlands in particular are monitored by a program that seeks to create a database for their sustainable management and preservation, although it includes water and sediments parameters only, for the hydrogeological characterization of the wetlands. In Figure 4 below we map the problems that were mentioned during both interviews and micro- workshops and their locations according to actors’ narratives. It goes without saying that data displayed there does not represent a complete picture of the problems faced in each location, but attempts to highlight both the complexity of the socio-environmental phenomena ahead and the extension of situated experiences that conform our network. In addition, since research activities in Spanish) that the authority has been conducting (in alliance with the municipal jurisdictions) since 2016 to evaluate the population’s environmental health by along the basin. In 2019 (ACUMAR, 2019) it also published a report for which it had begun working in 2016 with the National Scientific and Technical Research Council to produce an inventory of the basin’s wetlands, following the judicial demands as well as the Collegiate Body’s recommendations. #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 42 were carried out in the context of Covid-19 pandemic and lockdown restrictions, all actors, but especially community and policy actors, were overwhelmed by daily sanitary and economic emergencies, which may have changed their own priorities regarding socio-environmental problems. The construction of the Knowledge Coalition network is proposed in this project as a dynamic process. So far, we have connected with actors with experience in eight of the fourteen municipalities included in the Matanza-Riachuelo basin: Avellaneda, Almirante Brown, Merlo, Lanús, La Matanza, Lomas de Zamora, Esteban Echeverría, and Buenos Aires City. In most jurisdictions we map socio-environmental problems belonging to several categories, with important specificities in each of them. #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building 43 Figure 4: Basin map and socio-environmental problems classified in six categories #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 44 When the analysis is organised by types of actors, we could identify different problems’ prioritisation and also different practices aiming at addressing them, as shown below. CSOs and territorial organisations in our network frequently referred to issues related to social vulnerability, particularly in relation to poor access to housing and lack of access to public services such as drinkable water and sewage. Contamination of water and land coming from industrial and sewage waste and rubbish was also pointed out frequently among main problems. Since one of our micro-workshops was organised with neighbour associations defending natural reserves, green area conservation and changes in habitat conditions also turned up as important concerns. Finally, this type of actor was the one more prone to identifying problems they suffered that were directly related to policy action or inaction. CSOs’ and territorial organisations also reported activities to address those issues. These involve the organisation of complaints, mobilisations and environmental awareness campaigns against rubbish dumping, the destruction of natural reserves and the sale of public spaces. CSOs in particular, have a leading role in making visible main issues and in claiming for participation on both regulatory design and monitoring policy processes. Policy makers in our network identified problems similarly to communities but their priorities focus on the social vulnerability —housing deficit and lack of access to public services, but also basic needs such access to food, health and employment. Besides, they also mentioned environmental contamination problems which cannot be underestimated such as rubbish dumps and dumping of sewage and industrial effluents, and their associated health problems they may cause. The deficit of green areas and the risk of gentrification that can follow the improvements at the basin’s environment were also mentioned in some interviews, although not as main problems. #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 45 It must be noticed that actors from policy bodies have been in office for less than a year (governments in all jurisdictions changed in December 2019) and during pandemic time. Thus, although they mentioned some specific practices that were carried out in their jurisdictions to promote citizen participation (e.g., municipal forums for the conservation of green spaces) or environmental monitoring (e.g., creation of technical observatory of agrochemicals), they were still incipient and overpassed by other activities to deal with current emergency. Finally, members of research organisations tend to focus on single issues related to their research specialisation. They usually highlight how those issues are important for communities wellbeing. Water quality was one important research goal, and therefore, environmental contamination due to several causes included industrial, agricultural and sewage waste; rubbish dumps were highly mentioned. Researchers relate contamination with health problems and they mention that social vulnerability, especially the one associated with housing and lack of essential public services, only worsen the relation between contamination and health. In addition, the conservation of green areas was also mentioned as vital importance to avoid recurrent floods, aggravated by solid waste disposal obstructing streams, that cause evacuations and even deaths. As mentioned, activities and experiences by researchers from scientific organisations in our network were mostly related to analysing contamination, particularly in relation with water quality. For example, how water remediation tools used in other countries could be applied at the basin, or the elaboration of methods to control water use or the use of Citizen Science methods to monitor aquatic environments. There were also biological studies related to metal contamination, engineering studies for monitoring water bodies throughout the basin to anticipate floods and social studies on the effects of relocation on people and neighbourhoods. Most of these studies attempt to have an impact on public policy. #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 46 4.2.3 The Meanings and Processes of Citizen Participation in Policy Making (for Community and Policy Actors) and on Knowledge Production (for Scientific Actors) In our R&I action—and in citizen social science more generally—we envisage that people who engage are politically interested in changing a reality that affects them. They may contribute not just with information or data production about problems as defined by researchers, but also with their personal and situated experience in seeking for solutions. Yet, (their) participation could be organised in different ways by establishing the appropriate governance mechanisms. In this section we discuss how this idea is seen by different actors in the knowledge coalition, when we asked them about their understanding of the role of citizen participation. In our Knowledge Coalition network, citizen participation was recognised as having different roles which could be broadly associated to the different types of actors we interacted with. From a civil society perspective citizen participation in policy making has a democratising role; it is seen as the opportunity to be treated as equals in the definition of public policies priorities. In turn, from the perspective of public policy, citizen participation has a contributory role as it allows for a better identification of community priorities. If successful, this contributes to policy actions to be culturally or socially appropriated by the community, an important dimension for both the effective implementation as well as the sustainability of public policy. Academic actors were asked about the role of citizen participation in the production of scientific knowledge. In general, participation was seen as a route to improve the responsiveness of science. It was claimed that scientific projects could better reach community needs when working closely with them. In addition, due to that very same reason participation also contributed to the legitimisation of #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 47 science, before society and public policy actors, which is valued particularly during periods when public investment in science is questioned. Regarding policymaking processes, civil society actors see that community organisation is a necessary condition for participating in public policies, but it is not sufficient. Articulation with public policy bodies is also important to build trust relations that may be conducive to more effective participation. There are several important experiences in the basin where participation has accomplished important achievements, such as producing information about the sources and consequences of pollution (Pereira & Tobías, 2014), mapping and contrasting the results of the policy implementation (del Castillo & Fressoli, 2016; Radtke, 2018) and co-producing protocols for the relocations processes (Demoy et al., 2016). In all cases, there were social organisations and NGOs involved in the mobilization of different stakeholders. Yet, the organisations and community actors we interacted with identified a risk of citizen discouragement, since participation can be very demanding and—although included in the basin’s sanitation policy judicial sentence—there are no binding mechanisms created for participation to be translated into tangible public policy measures: existing mechanisms such as the “working roundtables” and public audiences are not binding. In addition, processes are so slow that can be frustrating. In turn, policy makers discussed the difficulty of balancing participation and deliberation with contexts of emergency decision-making (such as those imposed with the difficulties of Covid-19 times). But they also discussed the lack of appropriate mechanisms that would enable more engaged participation (innovating from the traditional consultative approaches). Finally, although as we mentioned there are some well-established experiences of Citizen Science in the basin, most researchers we interviewed do not consider citizen participation as an integral part of the knowledge production phase of the research cycle. They see it as part of University outreach #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 48 activities or introduced through traditional channels such as interviews to obtain data, or communication strategies, to share research outcomes, and in some cases, for social monitoring of environmental data. Outside specific Citizen Science networks, there is little knowledge about Citizen Science projects. Researchers working in Citizen Science projects, argued that it proved to be difficult to sustain collaboration with communities for a long time, especially because those activities are not recognised in scientific evaluation schemes and also because it was too demanding on time and energy to be ready to commit to those activities in the long run. Dealing with community expectations, especially in the context of social vulnerability, was also mentioned as an important barrier. 4.2.4 The First Steps Towards Platform Co-design One of the goals of the workshop was to identify current use of digital information by different stakeholders and the problems they face in general when looking for information. Participants discussed in small groups the information they use in their daily activities in the basin and we also asked specifically about some sources of information which share digital open data, to understand their experience with them in terms of access and use. There were 30 unique sources of information mentioned in the almost 50 post-its written in Jamboard. The distribution of digital vs. analogue sources was 20 to 6, with 4 that were classified as ambiguous (as they could be consulted either way and participants did not specify). We also found that in all break-out rooms participants mentioned at least one local source of information (from municipality’s websites or contacts to local press, organisations and neighbours). In relation to people's experience when using available information, the issues mentioned were: information’s obsolescence (due to lack of update or website maintenance); data format which made it difficult to reuse; visualization issues; and data fragmentation. #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 49 The second purpose of the workshop was to initiate more concrete discussions with members of the Knowledge Coalition on our R&I action goal of building a Citizen Science platform for mapping socio-environmental problems and promoting actions towards Environmental Justice. We divided the discussion on break-out rooms per thematic areas, but we found that there were some common topics that stood up in all rooms: to share experiences and narratives regarding the problem matter, and to facilitate networking and dialogue among different initiatives. The main concerns regarding the use of a digital platform that emerged in the three sessions were related to restrictions in technological infrastructure; lack of technical capabilities; potential misinterpretation or inadequate use of the uploaded information; and the need for data validation. 5. Concluding Remarks Our R&I action involves fairly complex and diverse socio-environmental phenomena in a large territory which is densely populated. In this context, we seek to articulate with a large network of allies, with previous experience and responsibilities in the basin. Network formation is dynamic and the participation of actors in the R&I activities will vary over time and the type of action. From our experience, we could argue that three variables affect engagement by different types of actors: thematic expertise and/or interest of participants; degree of synergies with their own activities in the basin and the specificities of the expected contribution for each planned action. We envisage that in order to address the complexity of socio-environmental issues involved in R&I action we need to enable participation from a diverse set of stakeholders, who could contribute to better identify problems, mobilise resources and facilitate socio-technical transitions, as the academic and policy literature suggest (Bäckstrand, 2003; Gallopín & Vessuri, 2006; Sauermann et al., 2020; Stirling, 2007). However, as these authors claim, the social impact of Citizen Science projects depends on overcoming several challenges that turn up when trying to guarantee scale, diversity and intensity of #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 50 participation (Den Broeder et al., 2018; Heiss & Matthes, 2017; Kythreotis et al., 2019; Sauermann et al., 2020). Challenges are related to how to sustain participation and how to respond to the time, technical and regulatory constraints that each participant faces in their own institutional and cultural context for action. Thus, to promote sustainability of such participation we need to link to interests and previous and future activities of these heterogeneous participants. That is why we believed a network structure of stakeholders’ participation is more appropriate than a fixed coalition of stakeholders. This implies that stakeholders will participate on and off in the different activities we propose but they are nevertheless well informed and connected to the project activities; they will actively participate when they find it suitable in terms of their own agenda. The challenge is then how to promote synergies among diverse stakeholder agendas without departing from the R&I action vision, that is to encourage citizen participation facilitated by digital tools to promote transformative actions towards Environmental Justice in the basin. The virtual environment imposed by Covid-19 pandemic added new challenges, particularly when considering the digital gap affecting people living in vulnerable conditions. Network formation is a dynamic process and therefore it is always a work-in progress. Yet, people in the Knowledge Coalition network have manifested explicit interest in participating and being informed on our activities. Therefore, despite important challenges ahead, especially in relation to Covid-19 related restrictions and uneven and poor digital infrastructure in the country, we think we have been able to create a yet incipient but growing network of actors interested and connected to our R&I action. The main challenge we encountered so far was to work in a lockdown situation with communities living in vulnerable situations with poor digital infrastructure. On more than one occasion, it was not possible to contact interested members of the community due to connectivity issues. Articulation with #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 51 public policy actors was also very complicated in this situation; we could do not more than acknowledge that they were buried in daily emergencies and we were not as successful as we expected in reaching them. Interviews and workshops turned virtual. For the former and for the cases the digital barrier was overcome, we faced some challenges in administering the Informed Consents. We learnt from the process and it went more smoothly over time. For the latter, we originally thought it may have been complex to gather a diversity of actors in a virtual environment, especially due to asymmetric power, digital capabilities and potentially conflicting interests. But after building trust through interviews, information communications and micro-workshops we managed to organised a very productive interactive workshop, some six months after the R&I action formally initiated. Challenges in relation to implementing the IC procedure were manifold. Firstly, we needed to design the tool almost from scratch. Informing participants of the research processes and obtaining their explicit consent is a common practice in biomedical projects in the country. However, in those cases people are the object of research and therefore tools used in those contexts are not straightforwardly adaptable to the participatory and collaborative approach of our R&I action. When the project began and prior to our initial activities we designed the IC forms and procedures. We documented all the participatory activities and made decisions in terms of the information we would share with the consortium’s members, discussing the types of personal data to be collected and measures of protection. We followed our colleagues’ recommendations and studied their forms’ proposals, as well as our local normative guidelines and examples of consent for other disciplines and developed our own for the different types of stakeholders and their participation, translating them to English as well. When we had to reprogram our activities due to the lockdown, we needed to design new tools for unforeseen activities such as micro and co-design virtual workshops. The impossibility of meeting face-to-face led us to innovate in our procedure, simplifying the language but also the format for providing information: FARN communication team produced a video and we implemented both oral #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 52 consent and electronic agreement through Google Forms, with identification assured by requesting confirmation with emails. Going through those challenges made us confident in our capacities to adapt our plans and remain flexible to new turns in the context of uncertainty. We have relied on stringent mechanisms for organisation and articulation among main partners. We established a fortnight team meeting fixed schedule since the beginning of the lockdown, which allowed us to thoroughly discuss necessary changes in original plans. We also documented decisions and established follow-up mechanisms. In addition, for building the Knowledge Coalition we rely on both organisations’ previous networks and we devote time and effort to build trust with new contacts, which is of paramount importance for the success of our project activities. We learnt it could be gained even in the absence of face-to-face interaction. We were also positively surprised by the good reception of digital tools among workshop participants. Yet we believe in future workshops and interactive activities we need to provide more time for oral discussions. In the co-design workshop, we realised that some of the group discussions were cut down before they could properly finish. Overall, we found that virtual interactions worked better in more institutionalised environments. However, in the case of community members along the basin we still need to experiment with alternative mechanisms. #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 53 6. References ACUMAR. (2018). Identificación de áreas prioritarias para intervenciones en la cuenca Matanza- Riachuelo. Análisis de riesgo ambiental. ACUMAR. (2019). Estudio de Humedales en la cuenca Matanza-Riachuelo. Estado de situación. ACUMAR. (2020). Informe de Mandas. Estado de cumplimiento y acciones. Bäckstrand, K. (2003). Civic Science for Sustainability: Reframing the Role of Experts, Policy-Makers and Citizens in Environmental Governance. Global Environmental Politics, 3(4), 24–41. https://doi.org/10.1162/152638003322757916 Biodiversidad de la cuenca Matanza-Riachuelo · iNaturalist. (n.d.). Retrieved 26 October 2020, from https://www.inaturalist.org/projects/biodiversidad-de-la-cuenca-matanza-riachuelo Cochero, J. (2018). AppEAR: A citizen science mobile app to map the habitat quality of continental waterbodies. Ecología Austral, 028(02), 467–479. https://bibliotecadigital.exactas.uba.ar/collection/ecologiaaustral/document/ecologiaaustral_v02 8_n02_p467 del Castillo, M & Fressoli, M. (2016). ¿Qué pasa Riachuelo? In M. Fressoli & V. Arza, The impact of citizen generated data in Argentina (pp. 21–26). CIVICUS DataShift. Demoy, M., Yacovino, P., Olejarczyk, R., Swistun, D., Campos, N., & Lekerman, V. (2016). Articulación entre la academia y la gestión pública. Reflexiones sobre la experiencia en procesos de relocalización involuntaria de población. Ponencia Presentada En Congreso Internacional Contested_Cities. Disponible En: Https://Bit. Ly/2iAv8FL [Fecha de Consulta: 08/10/2018]. #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 54 Den Broeder, L., Devilee, J., Van Oers, H., Schuit, A. J., & Wagemakers, A. (2018). Citizen Science for public health. Health Promotion International, 33(3), 505–514. https://doi.org/10.1093/heapro/daw086 Fressoli, M., & Arza, V. (2016). Discussion. In M. Fressoli & V. Arza, The impact of citizen generated data in Argentina (pp. 42–53). CIVICUS DataShift. Gallopín, G., & Vessuri, H. (2006). Science for sustainable development: Articulating Knowledges. In Interfaces between Science and Society (1st ed., pp. 35–52). Greenleaf Publishing Limited. https://doi.org/10.9774/GLEAF.978-1-909493-67-4_4 Haklay, M. (2018). Participatory citizen science. In Citizen Science: Innovation in Open Science, Society and Policy. UCL Press. Heiss, R., & Matthes, J. (2017). Citizen Science in the Social Sciences: A Call for More Evidence. GAIA - Ecological Perspectives for Science and Society, 26(1), 22–26. https://doi.org/10.14512/gaia.26.1.7 Hess, D. J. (2007). Alternative pathways in science and industry. MIT Press. Kythreotis, A. P., Mantyka-Pringle, C., Mercer, T. G., Whitmarsh, L. E., Corner, A., Paavola, J., Chambers, C., Miller, B. A., & Castree, N. (2019). Citizen Social Science for More Integrative and Effective Climate Action: A Science-Policy Perspective. Frontiers in Environmental Science, 7. https://doi.org/10.3389/fenvs.2019.00010 Mira, J. (2016). Activismo verde: Participación ciudadana por el derecho al ambiente sano en la Argentina. http://ri.conicet.gov.ar/handle/11336/28611 #5.1 Report on Knowledge Coalition Building The CoAct project has received funding from the European Union’s Horizon 2020 Research and Innovation programme under grant agreement No. 873048 55 Pasqualini, M. F., Bañuelos, C., Faure Montania, E., González, J., Hepp, Y., López, F. E., Malinovsky, V., & Mayo, P. (2018). Mapa de Riesgo Sanitario Ambiental de la Cuenca Matanza Riachuelo (ACUMAR, Ed.). ACUMAR. Pereira, P., & Tobías, M. (2014). Políticas de agua potable y saneamiento y demandas locales en el Área Metropolitana de Buenos Aires. MG Merlinsky, Cartografías Del Conflicto Ambiental En Argentina. Buenos Aires: CICCUS-CLACSO. Radtke, A. R. (2018). Caminos de la Villa: A case study in civic advocacy through crowdmapping [PhD Thesis]. Sauermann, H., Vohland, K., Antoniou, V., Balázs, B., Göbel, C., Karatzas, K., Mooney, P., Perelló, J., Ponti, M., Samson, R., & Winter, S. (2020). Citizen science and sustainability transitions. Research Policy, 49(5), 103978. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.respol.2020.103978 Stirling, A. (2007). A general framework for analysing diversity in science, technology and society. Journal of The Royal Society Interface, 4(15), 707–719. https://doi.org/10.1098/rsif.2007.0213 Verzeñassi, D., & Vallini, A. (2019). Transformaciones en los modos de enfermar y morir en la región agroindustrial de Argentina. ISSA. http://www.biodiversidadla.org/Documentos/Transformaciones- en-los-modos-de-enfermar-y-morir-en-la-region-agroindustrial-de-Argentina work_jjmyrtld4vetbiu26qooddg5ni ---- SYMPOSIUM: THE POLITICS OF PHILANTHROCAPITALISM Justice, Beneficence and the Modern Age Lenore T. Ealy Published online: 20 July 2011 # Springer Science+Business Media, LLC 2011 In an essay that fleetingly traverses the shifting sands of our perceptions of the role of philanthropists in our social and political order, Robin Rogers sets out to differentiate the emerging practices of philanthrocapitalism from philanthro- policymaking. Definitions are required, as we are immedi- ately caught up in something of a multi-syllabic nightmare, typifying our age when social analysis seems to depend more on our ability to coin new words for (supposedly) new phenomena than on our ability to take a trenchant look at the goings-on around us to determine whether there is anything new under the sun. For neologists Matthew Bishop and Michael Green, philanthrocapitalists are the super-wealthy—or super- influential (Bill Clinton is a pack leader, though the influence he peddles is largely of political rather than financial derivation)—who “are trying to apply the secrets behind [their] money-making success to their giving.” Rogers sums it nicely, “philanthrocapitalists want to bring the virtues of business to charity.” Setting aside for now discussion of the feasibility of this quest, we can define the second important term in Rogers’ essay, philanthro-policymaking. With this term, Rogers picks up on a core criticism of philanthrocapi- talism and differentiates the “agenda setting powers of the new global elite” from the tools they are developing and deploying to obtain better results from their charitable giving. This is an important distinction, and one that points to a perennial tension between justice and charity. Since the dawn of the industrial age, business, philanthropy and policy have engaged in a strange dance requiring the improvisation of new steps as practices of benevolence shifted from the Old World to the New. The Old World was characterized by systems of religious charity, paternalism rooted in agrarian cultures and courtly patronage. In the New World, urbanization and industrialization heightened percep- tions of social problems, and Enlightenment conceptions of equality and fraternity have seemed to demand more democratic forms of sanitary protection and welfare provision. Increasingly disembedded from a social structure that imposed various duties of beneficence, today’s successful entrepreneur often faces new questions about whether and how to share his bounty with the less fortunate. Before his ultimate transformation, Ebenezer Scrooge, that fictional functionary of the early “financial services industry,” encap- sulated the belief that policy could displace charity. When invited to make a voluntary subscription in support of the poor, Scrooge inquired of the door-to-door fundraisers, “Are there no prisons? … And the Union workhouses? … Are they still in operation? … The Treadmill and the Poor Law are in full vigour then?” Dickens tells us that Scrooge recoiled at the “ominous word ‘liberality’” and that he and Marley had been kindred spirits in this regard. Today’s super-wealthy, by contrast, seem to find some benefit in exploring their kindred spirit for doing good. For Rogers, the Giving Pledge, the voluntary commit- ment of a few dozen billionaires to devote a substantial portion of their wealth to charity, is philanthrocapitalism, and fairly benign. Meanwhile, the Good Club, a gathering in which the super-wealthy have met to identify social problems toward which they should combine and thus amplify their charitable efforts, is philanthro-policymaking, and potentially nefarious. We can see how persistently things stay the same despite how much then change when we consider how un-imaginative the Good Club’s target setting in fact has been. Rogers tells us that in 2009 the Good Club chose global population growth as a L. T. Ealy (*) Thinkitecture, Inc., 1415 Ironwood Dr W, Carmel, IN 46033, USA e-mail: lenoree@thinkitecture.com Soc (2011) 48:403–406 DOI 10.1007/s12115-011-9459-y focal problem. Are there subtle Malthusian echoes here of Scrooge’s cold-hearted response when informed that many of the poor would rather die than go to the poorhouse for relief? Unmoved by any sympathy with the dignity of these proud and apparently too abundant poor, Scrooge retorts, “If they would rather die…they had better do it, and decrease the surplus population.” There are deep ironies in the population skepticism of those most experienced in the creation of surplus wealth that suggest that our culture has not yet truly grasped or adapted to the new social conditions of democratic capitalism. Adam Smith, who was among the first to perceive the wealth-creating capabilities of the “system of natural liberty” that was possible when trade was freed from the shackles of mercantilist policy, was also among the first to perceive a need to explain why such liberty of exchange would not result in the dissolution of human sociality. Thus the same author who observed that it is from the self-interest of the tradesman, not from his benevolence, that we should expect our dinner would also write that “However selfish soever man may be supposed, there are evidently some principles in his nature, which interest him in the fortune of others, and render their happiness necessary to him….” In The Theory of Moral Sentiments, Smith explored the tension between justice and beneficence that has been a persistent philanthropic concern. It is largely this tension to which Rogers points us in her reflections upon the dangers of philanthro-policymaking. These dangers, she suggests, largely lay in the presumption of the super- wealthy to establish social ends outside of the public discourse and political mechanisms that modern demo- cratic nations have established for these purposes. The danger of this presumption, of course, is that the extreme wealth possessed by the philanthrocapitalists actually empowers them to pursue these ends to some effect. Were you (presuming few billionaires are reading these pages) and I to get together and decide to remake the world out of our own sense of good, the danger would be merely quixotic; without hundreds of millions of dollars to foment social change we would potentially do more harm to ourselves and our loved ones than to society at-large. When looking at the super-wealthy, however, we do find ourselves facing a variant of Locke’s important question, “Who Judge?” Should all redistribution of resources be adjudicated through democratic political institutions designed to approximate a public consensus on social ends? This question seems to be answered affirmatively by advocates of stronger charity regulation and policies such as “greenlining,” which would mandate more diverse representation in charita- ble governance as well as more proportional giving to minority communities (at this time largely defined around racial demographics). Even a cursory public choice analysis of collective decision making, however, suggests that further politicization of social justice concerns will fail to achieve the outcomes desired by social egalitarians suspicious of wealth and its potential misuse by the wealthy. The tension between justice and beneficence is quite real and deserves to be prominent in the public discourse of a free society. This discussion may be greatly enhanced if we re- examine Adam Smith’s framing of the tension. Smith states boldly that “beneficence…is less essential to the existence of society than justice.” (167) In establishing justice as the necessary foundation of society, Smith is far from commend- ing the modern conception of “social justice.” He anchors his discussion of justice on the necessity of remedial justice designed to resolve private injury to persons and property rather than on distributive justice which orders benefits. “The most sacred laws of justice, therefore, those whose violation seems to call loudest for vengeance and punishment, are the laws which guard the life and person of our neighbour; the next are those which guard his property and possessions; and last of all come those which guard what are called his personal rights, or what is due to him from the promise of others” (163). Justice in this common law framework is for Smith the “main pillar” of society, but beneficence is the “ornament which embellishes” (167) and is “always free, it cannot be extorted by force.” (155) Against this clarity of distinction, the modern pursuit of “social justice” inclines to confuse beneficence and justice, to drive into the realm of policy, and call for the enforcement by police powers, a desire for positive welfare equality that may come at the expense of social harmony by encouraging envy and resentment. A system in which justice absorbs beneficence will also diminish or explicitly proscribe the role of private charity and thus will be lost opportunity for the wealthy to exercise and model the virtues of sympathy through philanthropic endeavor. It was Karl Marx, of course, who drove this suspicion of charity and its practitioners to such radical conclusions, and in the end Rogers is tangling with dilemmas at the heart of the contest between Smith’s “system of natural liberty” and Marx’s critique of “capital- ism.” Rogers approves of the philanthrocapitalists’ volun- tary desire to do good, but remains attendant to the fact that combinations of wealth might amplify the potential harms, to individuals, communities, or nations, that could accom- pany philanthropy that comes with such huge monetary incentives and influence. So, how exactly should a free society treat the desires of the super-wealthy to do good? Must we minimize the potential that such large-scale gifts will actually generate greater harm (the nature of unreciprocated and unrecipro- cable gifts is in fact to generate servility)? If so, how do we do so while respecting the freedom of the super- wealthy as persons to exercise and experience the virtues of beneficence? 404 Soc (2011) 48:403–406 Rogers’ teasing out of philanthro-policymaking from philanthrocapitalism offers us one possible way to engage the discussion. At the turn of the twentieth century a predominant social concern was to limit the power of business combinations that resulted in commercial and manufacturing monopolies and diminished the benefits of competition. At the turn of the twenty-first century do we face the need to contemplate how philanthropic “combina- tions”—defined as an over-alignment of social ends by the titans of philanthropy—might likewise be detrimental to some perceived public good? Undoubtedly, unleashing a fire hose of philanthropic funds into any established community is bound to have a plethora of unintended and potentially harmful consequences. A danger, on the other hand, in pursuing greater regulation of philanthropy is that we disrupt the very creativity and potential for virtuous deliberation that philanthropy affords. Rigorously disavow- ing philanthro-policymaking would require, however, that we begin to seriously consider how to disentangle justice and beneficence and develop a more robust social theory of philanthropy than the third-party governance model of Lester Salamon. We must ask whether the vast government funding currently provided to “charitable” organizations to realize ends set by public policy is in fact also a dangerous form of philanthro-policymaking. Rather than a monistic philanthropy—whether one absorbed in and dictated by state policy or one seeking to align public policy with its own rationale and ends—we should promote a genuine social pluralism in a “market- place” of beneficence. Lest the term marketplace distract here, I should clarify that I think continuing to explore the proper relationships between the state, commerce, and philanthropy would help us move beyond the overly simplistic and sometimes silly effort to map business practices and metaphors onto our philanthropy. There are certainly many forms of charitable activity that can and should be moved out of the realm of not-for-profit organization and reconstituted as business activity, where the feedback mechanisms of prices and profit/loss signals could help us more effectively utilize resources for the provision of goods and services. Likewise, there should be a robust conversation in the business world about better responsiveness to consumers, especially those with limited power as consumers, and the trade-offs between short-term profit maximization and longer-term considerations of resource stewardship. Both of these conversations would help us move toward the more positive social deliberation commended by Richard Cornuelle, author of Reclaiming the American Dream and Healing America, who articulated the growing need we have to restore people’s confidence in their capacity for identify- ing and solving problems they perceive around them. In fact, it is the resumption of distributed social responsibility— diminished during the twentieth century by centralizing political trends and the accretion of power in expansive administrative welfare states—that can most help counter- balance the potential harm of the philanthropy of the super- wealthy. A people empowered by a confidence that they can engage, as Cornuelle puts it, in “concerted action, national [or international] in scope but outside government” can form a myriad of social enterprises and associations to realize their common hopes and dreams. Thus mobilized, the “wisdom of crowds” will also be more likely to generate more accurate assessments of the benefits or dangers posed by any potential philanthropic Trojan horse offered by the super-wealthy. Empowered to experiment and associate in pursuit of both their personal and shared goals, whether coincident or collaborate, people can help ensure that responsibility and resources flow toward competence and away from incom- petence. Reclaiming their capacities and competencies as producers of their communities rather than as clients of welfare agencies (whether those providing subsistence welfare or an expansive menu of middle-class entitlements), people can recover that civility and conviviality and the beneficent virtues that grow upon the foundation of justice in which rule of law not men prevails. The fact is that the super-wealthy are destined to be highly controversial, dramatic and alluring public figures in any age. Wealth can foster hubris with catastrophic results. There is perhaps less danger to civil society in the wealthy becoming exhibitionist consumers of luxury goods than in their growing desire to “do good.” While sumptuous living may breed the social ill of envy, it may also act as a spur to others to be industrious in seeking the potential benefits of entrepreneurship. The desire to do good is surrounded by moral hazards, and yet we remain hesitant to give up our visions of a more humane society. We thus have three basic options in dealing with the super-wealthy: leveling by progressively taxing them, looking on while they do what they will, or assisting them in discharging what we might call the Spiderman dictum, to him who is given great power is also given great responsibility. “Where the necessary assistance [men have of one another] is reciprocally afforded from love, from gratitude, from friendship, and esteem,” wrote Adam Smith, “the society flourishes and is happy.” Perhaps the most humane approach is to treat the wealthy among us as persons not as bank accounts. We might thus encourage and support them in their variety of aspirations to do good. Science fiction writer David Brin, in a provocative essay pre-dating the current attention to philanthrocapitalism, urges that the super-wealthy, those capable not of $1 million gifts but of $100 million gifts, should be encouraged to aspire to the most high risk, high reward projects imaginable. Brin proposes that “these would be projects that ill-suit the typical investment horizons of industry or government, the two dominant capitalizing forces Soc (2011) 48:403–406 405 of the 20th Century. Because each is constrained by accountability—to constituents or stockholders—govern- ments and corporations must control risk in ways that don’t always hamper an individual billionaire.” The dangers of encouraging bold philanthropy in a vacuum of accountability must not be ignored of course. Thus we are called back to contemplate at least three fundamental principles on which philanthropy should rest: 1) All people, from the most poor to the most wealthy, must be deemed capable of exercising the virtues of justice (refraining from injuring others) and benefi- cence (providing others positive assistance). This means that we resort to policy primarily as a barrier to injury and a promoter of the “system of natural liberty” which alone is an incubator of genuine virtue. 2) All people, from the most poor to the most wealthy, must be regarded with dignity as persons capable of developing personal goals, exercising personal responsibility, and engaging in voluntary reciprocal exchanges of benefits in the realms of both commercial trade and charitable activity. 3) Society must be conceived of foremost not as a utopian goal but as a dynamic space in which conditions of limited knowledge are best ameliorated through insti- tutions that are not designed and managed by an elite but rather emerge as the outcomes of voluntary human action and the deliberations among people seeing themselves engaged in a great journey together. Cornuelle suggests to us that a good society is that which emerges from “millions and millions of small caring acts, repeated day after day, until direct mutual action becomes second nature and to see a problem is to begin to wonder how best to act on it.” This is a vision fitting for the New World and the modern age, yet undiminished in its human capacities for the pursuit of virtue despite the transforma- tion of social, economic and political institutions that gave birth to the most expansively wealth-creating and philan- thropic nation in history. From this perspective, philanthro- capitalism may better refer not merely to the practices of a handful of super-wealthy but to the broader social dynamics that both reward entrepreneurship and continually expand opportunities to participate in what Deirdre McCloskey commends to us as the bourgeois virtues. Let’s invite the super-wealthy into a conversation with us about the potential we all have to be transformed through charity. Perhaps we may then all aspire, with the Scrooge who returned from his “intercourse with the Spirits,” to become “as good a friend, as good a master, and as good a man, as the good old city knew, or any other good old city, town or borough, in the good old world.” Lenore T. Ealy is director of the Project for New Philanthropy Studies at DonorsTrust and editor of the journal Conversations on Philan- thropy: Emerging Questions on Liberality and Social Thought. 406 Soc (2011) 48:403–406 Justice, Beneficence and the Modern Age << /ASCII85EncodePages false /AllowTransparency false /AutoPositionEPSFiles true /AutoRotatePages /None /Binding /Left /CalGrayProfile (Gray Gamma 2.2) /CalRGBProfile (sRGB IEC61966-2.1) /CalCMYKProfile (ISO Coated v2 300% \050ECI\051) /sRGBProfile (sRGB IEC61966-2.1) /CannotEmbedFontPolicy /Error /CompatibilityLevel 1.3 /CompressObjects /Off /CompressPages true /ConvertImagesToIndexed true /PassThroughJPEGImages true /CreateJDFFile false /CreateJobTicket false /DefaultRenderingIntent /Perceptual /DetectBlends true /DetectCurves 0.0000 /ColorConversionStrategy /sRGB /DoThumbnails true /EmbedAllFonts true /EmbedOpenType false /ParseICCProfilesInComments true /EmbedJobOptions true /DSCReportingLevel 0 /EmitDSCWarnings false /EndPage -1 /ImageMemory 1048576 /LockDistillerParams true /MaxSubsetPct 100 /Optimize true /OPM 1 /ParseDSCComments true /ParseDSCCommentsForDocInfo true /PreserveCopyPage true /PreserveDICMYKValues true /PreserveEPSInfo true /PreserveFlatness true /PreserveHalftoneInfo false /PreserveOPIComments false /PreserveOverprintSettings true /StartPage 1 /SubsetFonts false /TransferFunctionInfo /Apply /UCRandBGInfo /Preserve /UsePrologue false /ColorSettingsFile () /AlwaysEmbed [ true ] /NeverEmbed [ true ] /AntiAliasColorImages false /CropColorImages true /ColorImageMinResolution 150 /ColorImageMinResolutionPolicy /Warning /DownsampleColorImages true /ColorImageDownsampleType /Bicubic /ColorImageResolution 150 /ColorImageDepth -1 /ColorImageMinDownsampleDepth 1 /ColorImageDownsampleThreshold 1.50000 /EncodeColorImages true /ColorImageFilter /DCTEncode /AutoFilterColorImages true /ColorImageAutoFilterStrategy /JPEG /ColorACSImageDict << /QFactor 0.40 /HSamples [1 1 1 1] /VSamples [1 1 1 1] >> /ColorImageDict << /QFactor 1.30 /HSamples [2 1 1 2] /VSamples [2 1 1 2] >> /JPEG2000ColorACSImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 10 >> /JPEG2000ColorImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 10 >> /AntiAliasGrayImages false /CropGrayImages true /GrayImageMinResolution 150 /GrayImageMinResolutionPolicy /Warning /DownsampleGrayImages true /GrayImageDownsampleType /Bicubic /GrayImageResolution 150 /GrayImageDepth -1 /GrayImageMinDownsampleDepth 2 /GrayImageDownsampleThreshold 1.50000 /EncodeGrayImages true /GrayImageFilter /DCTEncode /AutoFilterGrayImages true /GrayImageAutoFilterStrategy /JPEG /GrayACSImageDict << /QFactor 0.40 /HSamples [1 1 1 1] /VSamples [1 1 1 1] >> /GrayImageDict << /QFactor 1.30 /HSamples [2 1 1 2] /VSamples [2 1 1 2] >> /JPEG2000GrayACSImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 10 >> /JPEG2000GrayImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 10 >> /AntiAliasMonoImages false /CropMonoImages true /MonoImageMinResolution 600 /MonoImageMinResolutionPolicy /Warning /DownsampleMonoImages true /MonoImageDownsampleType /Bicubic /MonoImageResolution 600 /MonoImageDepth -1 /MonoImageDownsampleThreshold 1.50000 /EncodeMonoImages true /MonoImageFilter /CCITTFaxEncode /MonoImageDict << /K -1 >> /AllowPSXObjects false /CheckCompliance [ /None ] /PDFX1aCheck false /PDFX3Check false /PDFXCompliantPDFOnly false /PDFXNoTrimBoxError true /PDFXTrimBoxToMediaBoxOffset [ 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 ] /PDFXSetBleedBoxToMediaBox true /PDFXBleedBoxToTrimBoxOffset [ 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 ] /PDFXOutputIntentProfile (None) /PDFXOutputConditionIdentifier () /PDFXOutputCondition () /PDFXRegistryName () /PDFXTrapped /False /Description << /CHS /CHT /DAN /ESP /FRA /ITA /JPN /KOR /NLD (Gebruik deze instellingen om Adobe PDF-documenten te maken die zijn geoptimaliseerd voor weergave op een beeldscherm, e-mail en internet. De gemaakte PDF-documenten kunnen worden geopend met Acrobat en Adobe Reader 5.0 en hoger.) /NOR /PTB /SUO /SVE /ENU (Use these settings to create Adobe PDF documents best suited for on-screen display, e-mail, and the Internet. Created PDF documents can be opened with Acrobat and Adobe Reader 5.0 and later.) /DEU >> /Namespace [ (Adobe) (Common) (1.0) ] /OtherNamespaces [ << /AsReaderSpreads false /CropImagesToFrames true /ErrorControl /WarnAndContinue /FlattenerIgnoreSpreadOverrides false /IncludeGuidesGrids false /IncludeNonPrinting false /IncludeSlug false /Namespace [ (Adobe) (InDesign) (4.0) ] /OmitPlacedBitmaps false /OmitPlacedEPS false /OmitPlacedPDF false /SimulateOverprint /Legacy >> << /AddBleedMarks false /AddColorBars false /AddCropMarks false /AddPageInfo false /AddRegMarks false /ConvertColors /ConvertToRGB /DestinationProfileName (sRGB IEC61966-2.1) /DestinationProfileSelector /UseName /Downsample16BitImages true /FlattenerPreset << /PresetSelector /MediumResolution >> /FormElements false /GenerateStructure false /IncludeBookmarks false /IncludeHyperlinks false /IncludeInteractive false /IncludeLayers false /IncludeProfiles true /MultimediaHandling /UseObjectSettings /Namespace [ (Adobe) (CreativeSuite) (2.0) ] /PDFXOutputIntentProfileSelector /NA /PreserveEditing false /UntaggedCMYKHandling /UseDocumentProfile /UntaggedRGBHandling /UseDocumentProfile /UseDocumentBleed false >> ] >> setdistillerparams << /HWResolution [2400 2400] /PageSize [595.276 841.890] >> setpagedevice work_jl7pqqmlovhafogfs4ak5uqgfy ---- TRYING TO DO JUSTICE TO THE CONCEPT OF JUSTICE IN CONFUCIAN ETHICS1 YANG MA0 T R Y I N G T O D O JUSTICE TO T H E CONCEPT O F JUSTICE IN C O N F U C I A N E T H I C S ’ b In his dealings with things under heaven chiin-tzu ( t h e noble man)2 is n o t invariably for or against anything. He just does what is ria (just, appropriate) X o n f u c i u s , t h e Analects (4.10)’ I. INTRODUCTION ‘ T h a t is not it at all. T h a t is not what 1 m e a n t , at all.” We o f t e n hear people saying this in everyday dialogues and conversations. This is a way for o n e t o protest others’s misinterpretations of her/his views. Very o f t e n , one may also a d d , “You are not doing justice t o what I said, at all.” What this means s e e m t o be t h e following: You a r e not doing justice t o what I said if y o u d o not render t h e correct meaning (cheng-yi ) t o what I said, because y o u are rendering something t h a t is n o t mine t o me, you are being insensitive t o t h e particular and unique meaning o f what I said. This use of t h e word “justice” indicates that hermeneutic issues are ethical ones. f This paper was originally presented a t a panel on “Confucian views of justice” a t an American Philosophical Association meeting. I was supposed t o read a paper, written in English, on Confucian views of justice. Under such conditions, 1 have been especially on the alert against a n y possible injustice I might d o to Confucian ethics. One seems t o have a special duty t o b e just when o n e writes on t h e concept of justice. Hence - t h e title “Trying t o d o justice t o the concepts of justice in Confucian Journal of Chinese Philosophy 24 ( 1 9 9 7 ) 521-551 Copyright 0 1 9 9 7 by Dialogue Publishing Company, Honolulu, Hawaii, U . S . A . 5 2 2 YANG X I A O ethic^."^ To regard hermeneutic issues as ethical ones is also a Confucian tradition. When a great Confucian scholar Chiao Hsiing w r o t e a c o m m e n - tary on t h e Mencius, h e entitled it Meng-tzu cheng-yi which could b e translated as ‘ T h e correct meaning o f t h e Mencius. ” Interestingly e n o u g h , early Confucian Hsiin Tzui used it.’ Therefore, I have t o take seriously t h e following objection: One may immediately object to this paper by saying t h a t t h e m o m e n t 1 write down t h e title, I have already d o n e injustice (or violence) t o Confucian ethics; when I u t t e r t h e Engfish words “the concept of justice in Confucian ethics,” which imply that Confucian ethics d o have a concept that can be expressed b y t h e Enghsh word “justice”, I a m imposing a modern Western concept o n Confucius, Mencius and their followers i n ancient China. The injustice I have d o n e t o t h e m is double, because t h e y are neither m o d e r n nor Western. To p u t this objection in o n e sentence, it is impossible for me to do justice to t h e concept of justice in Confucian ethics if I write in a language that is n o t Confucians’s language. Let me first clarify what is really going on in this objection. As w e shall know a t t h e end o f this paper, this objection cannot b e fully responded to h e r e . In the one-sentence version o f the objection t h e term “language” is actually used in t w o ways and t h u s can mean t w o things: h cheng-yi f originally means “upright and just”. T h a t is, a t least, h o w t h e i) a particular ordinary language like Chinese or English; let me call it the ”linguistic sense” o f the term “language ” ; ii) a particular set o f categories and concepts (when T h o m a s Kuhn says that Einstein and Newton speak two different “languages,“ he does not mean t h a t t h e former speaks in German and the latter in English) let me call this its “conceptual sense”. Very o f t e n , when people use t h e term langwge in its conceptual sense, they p u t i t into quotation marks (so o n e native English speaker m a y say JUSTICE IN CONFUCIAN ETHICS 5 2 3 t o another native English speaker: w e can’t understand each o t h e r ; it’s as if we are speaking in t w o “languages.”) Accordingly, there are actually t w o things going on in t h e objection. The first is the objection that a Western language (English) is not appro- priate in t h e Chinese context. However, it does n o t particularly have to d o with Confucians; it applies t o the case where o n e talks a b o u t Taoism in E n a s h , or, about Aristotle i n French, etc. T h e second objection is that t h e set o f Western categories and concepts - the concept o f justice being part of it - is n o t appropriate to apply to Confucian ideas. Thus there are actually two objections. In section 11, I shall t r y to clear u p some conceptual confusions that are involved in b o t h objections and introduce a crucial distinction between c o n c e p t and conception. (Notice that 1 use “concept,” not “conception,” in t h e title o f this paper). In section 111, I shall propose a working formu- lation o f t h e concept of justice, which shows h o w t h e term “just” is used a n d what it is like to have a concept of justice, m o r e specifically, what it is like if it is the case that there is t h e concept o f justice i n Confucian ethics. Section IV is a textual analysis which shows h o w , in the Analects and t h e Mencius, t h e term yia is used in the w a y described in the working formulation o f the concept of justice. That is to say, we can indeed fmd the concept o f justice in Confucian ethics. However, i t will also be shown that t h e Confucian understanding of the concept is a very particular o n e . I shall come back to t h e objections in section V . It is a b o u t t h e very possibility o f doing justice t o the concept of justice in Confucian ethics while writing in English. Interestingly enough, what surprised even myself is that the justice of “trying to d o justice” turned o u t t o b e the same kind of justice of “the concepts of justice in Confucian ethics.” There- fore, this paper becomes a n a t t e m p t t o treat t h e concept o f justice in Confucian ethics in a Confucian m a n n e r , or in a manner t h a t is just in its Confucian sense. 5 2 4 YANG XIAO 11. SOME CONFUSIONS AND THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN CONCEPT AND CONCEPTION Almost everyone who ever talks about the issue of justice in Con- fucian ethics in Engllsh has been keenly aware of, and often overwhelmed b y , two obvious “facts” about the differences between Confucian language and Western language both in its linguistic and conceptual sense. The first “fact” is actually about its linguistic difference, the second conceptual difference. In this section, I want to say a few words about some possible confusions involved in interpreting these two facts. Let me start with the first one. Thomas H.C. Lee begins hs article ‘The Idea of Social Justice in Ancient China” by saying that “One of the most important characteristics of Chinese social philosophy is its con- spicuous lack of one word [my emphasisjthat we can readily translate as ’justice.”’6 R P . Peerenboom also claims: “There is not even u term [my emphasis] for ‘justice’ in the classical lexicon of Confucius.”’ He also dismisses what he calls “the most likely candidate,” the Chinese character yia, by saying that it “has been translated in terms associated with justice - righteousness, duty, principle, obligation - though never, t o my knowledge, consistently as justice. Moreover, David Hall and Roger Ames have argued quite convincingly that. such Western-influenced langu- age is inappropriate in the Confucian context.”’ I would Wte to make two remarks about ttus linguistic fact. The first one is that we cannot presuppose that there must be one word or term in Chinese that corresponds to the English word “justice.” There might be a complex relationship between the Enghsh word “justice” and a set of Chinese words, not just one Chinese word. Or, if there is a corres- ponding relationship between “justice” and a Chinese word, it may be that only some uses of this Chinese word, not necessarily the other uses of the word, can be said to mean “justice.” As I shall show later, this applies to the Chinese word yia. In fact, the reluctance of translatingyia as justice also has to do with the extremely diverse uses of “yia” in Confucian ethics. I shall say more about this later. Here let me just say that, from JUSTICE IN C O N F U C I A N ETHICS 5 2 5 the linguistic fact that there is no one word that can be readily translated as justice, it is a fallacy to draw the conclusion that there is no concept of justice in China.’ The conclusion one can draw is simply that there is no such neat word-to-word correspondence between Chinese and Western thought. We may not expect that complex concepts such as justice would be like concepts such as “water”or “table,”which usually can have a neat word-to-word translation in another language. The second remark I want to make is about Peerenboom’s claim that, since “justice” is a part of “Western-influenced language,” it thus cannot be a proper translation of yia. Two senses are packed in the term “language”; from the fact that two people speak two different languages in its linguisric sense, we cannot immediately infer that they must speak two different “languages” in its conceptual sense. One cannot say that Chinese-speaking people must think differently from Enghhspeaking people. It may turn out that they do think differently ;it may also turn out that they d o not. Or, it may turn o u t that neither is thecase -that is, a detailed study may show that they thlnk somerimes differently and sometimes (e.g., when it comes to the concept of justice) similarly. This seems to be a conclusion that is hard to swallow for philosophers who always love the modal term “always” but never “sometimes”. However, one should not expect to draw neat and systematic conclusions if she tries to d o justice t o the particular. As we shall see, this is the spirit of Confucian conception of justice. I shall say more about this in the last section. The second “fact”, which almost everyone emphasizes, is that in traditional Confucian ethics there is no modern liberal conception of justice in terms of equal liberties and inalienable individual rights. Liberals in today’s China have put the blame on traditional Confucian ethics for the absence o f the conception of individual right in modern China. How- ever, this absence is not a unique feature that only ancient Confucian ethics has. Aristotle’s ethics does not have the modern conception of equal liberties and rights, either. Liberalism is a quite recent phenomenon even in the West.” 5 26 YANG X l A O In discussions concerning justice and societies of the past, a question has often been asked. (q1)Can we say that ancient Confuciunism or ancienr Con- fucian China, is unjust in its modern liberal sense? This is a very complicated issue. I can’t go into it here. I would simply say that this question should not be confused with the following question concerning a present society. (q2)Can we say that today ’s China, given that it can be called a Confucian country,’’ is unjust in its modern liberal sense? The first question is about “ancient China”, the second “today’s China.” A lot of arguments for the idea that one cannot apply the conceptions of equal liberties and rights to today’s China are based on the confusion of these two questions. What those arguments actually establish is simply that we should say no to the fust question; since the two questions are confused, people can be easily misled to believe that the it has been argued that we should say no to the second question as well.” So let me make it clear that the following argument regarding a relativistic view of ancient Confucian China is about ancient Confucian China and cannot be applied to today’s China, even if it can still be called a Confucian country. I want to call attention to the fact that one can say no t o the first question and say yes t o the second at the same time. That one can d o so is due t o the following two crucial differences between ancient China and today’s China. i) In today’s China, the idea of liberty and right is, of course, not yet totally institutionalized; it has, neverthe- less, become part of the political-legal culture of the nation.” T o a certain degree, it has become a (potential) JUSTICE IN C O N F U C l A N ETHICS 5 2 7 overlapping consensus, by a p p e a h g to which civil dis- obedience can even be justified in today’s China.I4 All these cannot apply t o ancient China. ii) Today’s China is n o t a homogeneously Confucianist country, even if one still wants to call it a Confucian nation (however, if that could be done, then, in a similar way, one can also say that the pluralistic society of the U.S. is a Christian nation). It seems safe t o say that in today’s China Confucianism, as a revival tradition, is not the dominant political-legal culture as it used to be in ancient China; it has to compete with other conceptions of good life, including liberalism. I am aware that these two observations are controversial. However, here what I really need for my argument regarding a relativisitic view of ancient Confucian China is a weaker claim, which is the following: it was historically impossible for Confucius to have a modern liberal conception of justice in terms of liberties and rights, whereas such a modern liberal conception has become a historical possibility in today’s China.” It seems to be a widely shared intuition that it is not just (fair) t o require Confucius or Aristotle to have a modern liberal conception of justice, which was historically unavailable to them. If one thinks historically, as Hegel does, one will see that i t takes time (history) for e t h c a l ideas to become possible and actual. And, accordingly, a criticism of a n age for not living up to an ideal will remain an empty and impotent “moral” criticism until the ideal, on which the criticism ,is based, becomes histori- caUy possible. One does not have to accept Hegel’s whole controversial philosophy of history t o see this point. Bernard Williams, who has criti- cized Hegel’s redemptive conception of history,16 also shares this intui- tion. He says, 5 2 8 YANG X I A O O n e can define a relativistic view o f justice. There is some pressure, if o n e thinks historically a t all, t o see m o d e r n con- ceptions o f social justice, in terms o f equal rights, for instance, as simply n o t applying to hierarchical societies o f t h e past. T h e obvious fact that those societies would not satisfy t h e conditions I q u o t e d from Rawls in chapter 5 seems relevant neither t o those societies nor to the merits of Rawls’s criteria as proposed f o r m o d e r n societies.” T h e two conditions Williams q u o t e d from Rawls are the famous f u n d a - mentai principles of justice in terms of equal liberties and rights, w h i c h , as Rawls says characterize t h e liberal conception o f j u s t i c e . Notice the term beging used here is “conception,” n o t “concept .” Rawls makes a very important distinction between c o n c e p t i o n and c o n c e p t . the concept of justice is about t h e basic terms of people’s asso- ciation, people m a y disagree a b o u t which specific principle of justices should define t h e basic terms of their association - i.e. t h e y m a y have disagreement a b o u t t h e conception of justice, but t h e y each have a concept of justice, which is abstract and vague sufficiently t o command widespread assent so that it “would act, in public argument as well as private rumination, as a kind of plateau on which further thought and argument are built. As Rawls puts i t , “it seems natural t o think of the concept of justice as distinct from the various conceptions of justice and as being specified b y t h e role which ... [its] different conceptions have in C O ~ O I I . ” ~ ~ So we c a n say that liberals a n d utilitarians have a different conception o f justice, b u t t h e same concept of justice. T h e ancient Confucian society, a hierarchical society of t h e past, clearly does not have these two principles o f justice, which specify the liberal conception of justice. There is t h e n some pressure not t o apply the m o d e r n liberal conceprion of justice to ancient China. Under this pressure of relativistic view of justice, o n e might be easily tempted to. conclude that ancient Confucian China does not even have a concept of justice. I shall call someone a “radical relativist” if s h e believes that J U S T I C E IN C O N F U C I A N ETHICS 5 2 9 hierarchical societies of the past, such as ancient China, d o not even have a concept of justice. It seems clear that, if we want t o see whether Confucians have a concept of justice, the concept of justice we should defme has to be suf- ficiently empty, broad and abstract. That is to say, this concept of justice should be formulated not in terms of particular ideas such as equal rights, which can only be found in a modern liberal conception of justice; it should be a concept that is shared by all the particular conceptions of justice, includmg the very peculiar modern liberal conception of justice. Ill. WHAT IS IT LIKE TO HAVE A CONCEPT OF JUSTICE? In the passage I quoted from Williams in the last section, he argues that there is some truth in a relativistic view of justice and hence there is some pressure to see the “modern conception of justice in terms of equal rights” as simply not applying to hierachical societies of the past. How- ever he also argues that the concept of social justice is “a special case in relation to relativism” and that “Justice and injustice are certainly ethical notions and arguably can be applied to past societies as a whole, even when we understand a good deal about them.”’0 Notice that here what can be applied t o past societies is not the “modern conception of justice in terms of equal rights,” but “justice as ethical notions.” I read what he says as meaning that, although the modern conception of justice in terms of equal rights does not apply to societies of the past, the concept of justice seems to be a non-relatively shared one. That is t o say, Williams is not a radical relativist. This is especially obvious from what he immedi- ately says right after the passage I quoted in the kast section. Yet there are strong pressures for the justice or injustice of past societies not merely to evaporate in the relativism of distance. Even if we refuse to apply to them determinately modern ideas, some conceptions of justice were used in those 5 30 YANC X l A O societies themsehes [my emphasis] and it is not a pun or a linguistic error t o call them that.” However, the issue is not as simple as it sounds. How does one know that the proposition that “some conceptions of justice were used in those societies themselves” is true? The truth of this proposition is exactly what a radical relativist denies. Especially in the cases where the past society had a different language, how d o we know that some concept of justice was used i n that society? It seems that we cannot know it unless we have already translated a certain word in that language as “justice’ or ‘ S U S t . ” Then that would be begging the question. For what a radical relativist denies is exactly the possibility of translating any word in that language as ’justice” or ’just.” 1) the past society was an English-speaking o n e , ii! !he past society was ancient China. Let us further suppose the past society we are concerned with is medieval England, and we find the following sentence written by Shakespeare in 1 6 0 1 . “He was my Friend, faithful, and just to me.” A Radical relativist could insist that, although Shakespeare spoke the same language (English) as we do today, it is only the same language in its linguistic sense, he actually spoke a different “language” in its conceptual sense. He has a totally different set of concepts and categories. A radical relativist may say that “We and Shakespeare d o not even share the same concept of justice.” In this case, Williams could indeed argue convincingly against this radical relativism by saying that Let us consider t w o possible cases. (E) It is not a pun or a linguistic error to call the concept, which is expressed by the word. ‘‘just” Shakespeare used, a concept of justice. However when we move to the second case where the past society is ancient Chma, it seems that Williams’s strategy wouldn t work. For it cannot convince anyone b y saying that JUSTICE 1N C O N F U C l A N ETHICS 531 (C) I t is not a pun or a linguistic error to call the concept of justice used in ancient China “the concept of justice.” It will be tautological to call the concept of x used in society y “the concept of x . ” A radical relativist will not be convinced by this. The statement (C) has already presupposed that there is the concept of justice in ancient China, which is exactly what we want to prove and a radical relativist denies That is t o say, we cannot refute radical relativism at such an abstract level. We have to do a detailed study of how certain words in ancient Chinese are used, and how they are used in what kinds of practices and contexts (e.g., in the practice of accepting gifts). If, through this study, we can manage to show that there are uses, at least some uses, of a certain word - let us call it “c” - in ancient Chinese which are similar to the uses of “just” then, we can say, (C) I t is not a pun or a linguistic error to call the concept, which is expressed by the word “ c ” in ancient Chinese, a concept of justice. More specifically, in order to show that the Chinese character “c” expresses the concept of justice, one has to show that the word “c” is used - at least sometimes - in the same way the word ‘>ust” is used as defined by a formulation of the concept of justice. This is what I am going t o d o in the next section. And, the word “c” will turn out to be the character ‘>yia” which expresses one of the central concepts in Confucian ethics. Notice that it does not require that the word ‘)ia” always behaves like the word ‘?just”. The fact that sometima i t behaves like “just” is enough for proving that there is a concept of justice in ancient China. A parallel case might be helpful here. The Greek term dikaws, as Gregory Vlastos observes, could be used to cover all soclal conduct which is morally right and its sense is thus much broader than ’just.”n Most scholars have translated it as “just.” So does Vlastos. For it is enough 5 3 2 YANC. XIAO that some of its uses are similar to the uses of ‘Tust.” This is also how Rawls argues that his concept of justice can be said to ‘’tally with tradi- tion,” by tradition he means Aristotle’s concept of justice, which is expressed by the Greek term dikaios or d i k ~ i o s y n 2 . ~ ~ Before we move to the next section, where we will figure o u t the condition under which Confucius and Mencius would use y i a , the last tool we need is a formulation of the concept of justice, which shows under what condition we will use the term “just.” Then we will be able to compare this condition with the condition under which Confucius and Mencius use the word “pa”. I would like to propose two formulations of a working concept of justice and 1 shall show that the second one is appropriate for our purpose in this paper. The first one is a modified formulation that is found in Rawls’s later work Political Liberalism, which is different in many respects from his early work A Theory ofJustice. However, the distinction between concept and conception is still there; he says in Political Liberalism, This pair [of concept and conception] is distinguished as they were in Theory, pp. 5f. Roughly, the concept is the meaning of a term, while a particular conct!ption includes as well the principles required to apply it. ... People can agree on the meaning of the concept of justice and still be at odds, since they affirm different principles and standards for deciding those matter^."'^ What he means by *those matters” is, as he puts i t , to make “distinctions between persons in assigning bcsic rights and duties, ...[ And to establish] proper balance between competing claims’’ (ibid, my emphasis). This formulation is not broadly framed, because it is still formulated in terms of basic rights which can only be found in the modern liberal conception of justice. Nevertheless, I think, Rawls’s concept of justice need n o t be so narrowly defined. What is being assigned need n o t be *basic rights and duties;” let us modify it by replacing them by “things,” which can be JUSTICE IN CONFUCIAN ETHICS 5 3 3 a variety of things, such as wealth and rank, profits, a wife,2s respect, honor, and so on. Another problem with Rawls’s concept is that it seems t o pre- suppose the existence of a nationstate or the “basic structure” of a nation- state because he sometimes also says that the concept of justice is about the basic terms in which citizens of a nation-state design their basic structure. Formulated in this way, the concept of justice would apply only to the basic structure, not to actions and persons. But we need a concept of justice that can apply t o basic structures (or institutions) and actions and persons as well. J6 The second formulation, which is the one I am going t o use in this paper, is form H.L.A.Hart. In fact, Rawls borrows the distinction between concept/conception from Hart.” But it seems that h e does not notice that Hart’s formulation is a broader one. According t o Hart, “justice is traditionally thought of as maintaining or restoring a balance o r propor- tion, and its leading precept is often formulated as T r e a t like cases alike’; though we need t o add to the latter ‘and treat different cases differently:” And this ‘‘traditional precept” is a “concept” of justice, not a “conception” of justice. Hart says, [Tlhough ‘Treat like cases alike and different cases differently’ is a central element in the idea of justice, it is by itself incomplete and, until supplemented, cannot afford any determinate guide t o conduct. This is so because any set of human beings [ o r s i t ~ a t i o n s ] ~ ~ will resemble each other in some respects and differ from each other in others and, until it is established what resemblance and differences are relevant, ‘Treat like cases alike’ must remain an empty We can ask whether a person treats like cases alike and different cases differently, or whether anaction is conducted in such a way that like cases are treated alike and different cases differently. Formulated in this way, the concept of justice can apply t o actions, persons, etc, not just t o the 5 34 YANC X l A O basic structure of a society. I also want t o express this formulation in a different version, which will be proved t o be more useful in the next section. Hart’s version is the following: (J) To be just is t o treat like cases alike and different cases differently. One may also say that those like cases form a “kind” (the Chinese charac- ter: lei”) and that different cases belong t o different “kinds” therefore, (J) can also be expressed as follows: (J) To be just is t o treat cases that belong t o the same kind alike and cases that belong t o different kinds differently. Obviously, this is a concept of justice, because it remains an empty form until it is established, by a particular conception of justice, which could be a system of classifications telling us specifically what cases form the same kind (leim) and what cases belong t o different kinds. In the next section, I am going to show that the concept expressed by the term yia in Confucian ethics is a concept of justice. More specific, in order to prove this, what we need t o find is the following: (Y) To be yia is t o treat like cases alike and different cases differently. Or t o formulated in terms of kinds (leim), (Y’)To be yia is t o treat cases that belong t o the same kind (leim) alike and cases that belong to different kinds differently. JUSTICE IN CONFUCIAN ETHICS 5 35 IV. TEXTUAL ANALYSIS: HOW Yp IS USED IN CONFUCIUS AND MENCIUS The character yia occurs twenty-four times in the Analects, one hundred and eight times in the Mencius. Its uses are diverse. Ch’en Ta- &’in a contemporary scholar of Confucianism, once i n a paper classified the uses of yia in the Mencius into four kinds: 1) self-regarding morality 2) others-regarding morality; 3) norms of values; 4) principles of human affairs. In a book published later, he criticized himself for making a farfetched classification of the uses of ria. In the end he has given up this classification. What he later did was t o put together similar uses of the word in the text without imposing his own classification system. What came out was an amazing classification: a ) y i a of respecting the elderly and obeying the elder brothers, b) yia between the ruler and the ministers; c) yia that has t o d o with taking and giving; d) yia of the heartlmind of shame, e) y i that is said t o be the human path or way f ) yia that conflicts with profits, g) yia that is said t o be internal; h) yia that is said t o be common yia of the world.30 And this list can go o n and on. What should we make out of this? How should we explain such a bizarre classification? How is it possible t o use one word t o cover so many different uses? Fortunately, here we d o not need t o answer these questions. It may be that there is a common thread underlying all these diverse uses; or the uses have no thread running through but only a “family resemblance,” or, another interpretation is that Mencius’s use of the word is simply another particular case of the “oriental way of thinking and classifying” which is always exotically chaotic and incoherent.” As I said earlier, for my purpose in this paper, it would be sufficient if I can show that some uses of yza satisfy the formulation (Y) or (Y)’. There- fore, I will just focus on one group of uses of yia that has to d o with taking, having or accepting things (group c) above.” Confucius says that one of the three characteristics of a complete person is that the complete person t h i n k s about ria at the moment of 5 36 Y A N C XlAO having profit (14.12). At two places, Confucius says that a chiin-tzib would think about yia a t the moment of gaining something (19.1 and 16 10). In the Analects and the Mencius, the objects that can be taken, gained and accepted could be a variety of things: wealth and rank (7.16, 4.5), profit (14.12), a state (7A:34), the tyrant o f a state (3B:5), the office of minister (5A.8), a wife (6B.1), food (6B:l) a present of a hundred yi of gold of superior quality (2B:3), the Empire (3B:4), a basketful of rice (3B:4). Let g be any one of the things listed above. In all the above cases, Con- fucius and Mencius claim that one should always ask “Is it yia t o take Cpain, accept) g ? rr33 If we say that, for Confucius and Mencius, yia is the principle for taking, gaining and accepting things, we have t o qualify it by adding a lot of warnings.” One of them is the following: the principle” of yia does not have the form of what I shall call “strictly universal principle.” Here are some examples of strictly universal principles: ( U , ) It is always just or right to takeg. (Or, ‘Always takeg.’? ( U , ) It is always just or right not t o take g. (Or, “Always d o not take g.”) I shall call someone a “strict universalist” if she believes that a principle of justice must take the form of a strictly universal principle - i.e., a principle of justice can only take either the form ( U , ) or the form (LIZ). For a strict universalist, one cannot say, “It is just (or right) at rime t to take g.” For it does not make sense t o say that something is just (right) at one particular time; it is either always right or always wrong - this is the strictly universal “grammar” of the term “just” or “right”. That is t o say, for strict universalism, a principle of justice cannot have the following form: JUSTICE IN CONFUCIAN ETHICS 5 37 (P) It is sometimes right or just, and sometimes not, t o take g . I shall call those “particularists” who think that the principle of justice should take the form of (P) Let us assume someone accepts a gift or present at time t l and refuses a present a t time t2 For a strict universalist, if she is just t o accept a present at t , then, she must be unjust at t 2 . All the cases of gift-taking, regardless of what a particular circumstance a case is in, form one homo- genous kind, and all cases of gift-taking thus must be treated alike. One only has two options: i) either t o accept all the gifts, regardless of who offers, when they are offered, in what manner they are offered, what particular situation one is in; or, ii) to refuse all the gifts, regardless of who offers, when they are offered, in what manner they are offered, what particular situation one is in. Accordindy, strict universalism can also be expressed as follows, (U)’ All cases of gift-taking form one homogeneous kind and should be treated alike. That is t o say, for a strict universalist, a principle of justice cannot have the following form: (P)’ Some cases of gift-taking form a kind, and some cases of gift-taking form a different kind. The cases belonging t o the same kind should be treated alike and the cases belonging t o a different kind should be treated dif- ferently. Notice that both strict universalism (U)’ and particularism (F‘)’ share the idea that cases belonging t o the same kind should be treated alike and cases belonging t o different kinds should be treated differently. That is to say, they share the same concept ofjustice. But since they have totally different particular ideas about what caes belong t o which kind, they have 5 38 YANG X l A O different conceptions of justice. I now want to show that the debate between Ch’en Chen‘ and Mencius in 2B:3 is actually a debate between a strict universalist and a particularist. Ch’en Chen‘, according t o Chao Ch’is, is one of Mencius’s disciple^.^' He seems to be a strict universalist. He somehow believes that the principle of accepting gifts should be either “Always accept gifts” or “Always d o not accept gdts.” He once asks Mencius: T h e other day in Ch’i you refused t o accept a present of a hundred yi of gold from the King, but in Sung you accepted a present of seventy yi in Hsiieh you likewise accepted fifty yi. And, Ch’en Cen‘ objects to Mencius’s actions by saying that, If your refusing t h e gift in the first case was right, your accepting in the latter cases must be wrong;on the other hand, if your accepting in the latter case was right, your refusing in the first case must be wrong. You cannot escape one or the other of these two alternatives. (2B:3) To put his point in other words: You have treated cases of gift-taking differently; you should have had one single universal way t o treat all cases of gift-taking. For either it is always right to accept gifts or it is always wrong t o accept gifts. One only has these two alternatives, there cannot be a third alternative, which is that it is sometimes right and sometimes wrong to accept gifts. And, this is exactly what Mencius denies in his answer to Ch’en Chen‘ In 2B:3, Mencius is recorded as replying t o Ch’en Chen‘ in the following way. He says, “Both my refusal and acceptance were right.” Then he goes o n to give his explanations about how the latter t w o cases are similar and hence are treated alike and how the first case is different from t h e two cases and hence is rightly (‘justly) treated in a way different from the two cases. W h a t he does is t o treat similar like cases alike, and different cases differently. Mencius, like Confucius, has n o absolute yes or absolute no (wu-ko-wu-pu-kou) regarding what is t o be done JUSTICE IN CONFUCIAN ETHICS 5 3 9 (18.18). He is not invariably for o r against anything he does what is appropriate. Mencius can be perfectly characterized b y Confucius’s fol- lowing saying,“chiin-fzub is not invariably for or against anything. He just does what is yra.” (4.10) So it seems that yia does satisfy the formu- lation (Y).= When Mencius left Ch’i, on the way Ch’ung Yuv, a disciple, asked: Master, you look somewhat unhappy. I heard from you the other day the principle that “Chiin-fzu reproaches neither Heaven nor man.”’ Mencius answered, ‘This is one time (shihw); that was another time (shihW)” (2B: 13). The concrete applications of the Confucian general principle b “Chiin-tzu reproaches neither Heaven nor man” thus vary from time t o time. In fact, Mencius calls Confucius ’the sage of shihw” (the sage whose actions are timely) (5B: 1). By this, Mencius means that “He was the sort of man who, when it was proper to hasten his departure, hastened his departure, when it was proper t o delay it, delayed it when it was proper t o remain in the state, remained in the state, when it was proper t o take office, took office, all according t o circumstances” ( S B : I , also see 2 A : 2 ) . Let me end this section with one of m y favorite anecdotes in the Analects, which is another good example t o illustrate the Confucian concept of ria. Confucius was once being asked by two of his disciples the same question: “Should one immediately put into practice what one has learned? ” The Master gave totally different answers. T o student Tzu-lu, it was “As your father and elder brothers are still alive, you are hardly in a position t o put immediately into practice what you have learned.” To another student Jan Yu, the answer was simply “Yes. One should.” When the master was asked why his answers were different, he replied, “Jan Yu holds himself back. It is for this reason that I tried t o urge him on. Tzu-lu has the energy of two men. It is for this reason that I tried t o hold him back” (1 1.22). What the anecdote shows is that Confucius is extremely sensitive t o the richness and complexity of the particular. He cultivates people who have different particular characters in different ways. He refuses t o insist b 5 40 YANG X l A O o n absoluteness, refuses t o be inflexible (see 9.4). For Confucius, chin- tzu must have the sensibility t o the particular, t o the richenss and com- plexity o f the particular. The above anecdote is a perfect example to illustrate what exactly Confucius means in the passage I cited as a m o t t o for this paper (4.10). Confucius is not generally (abstractly) for the general rule “Put into practice immediately what one has learned”; nor is he generally (abstractly) against the general rule. His sensibility to the particular makes him distrust any of this kind of general rules. In certain concrete situations he is “concretely” for it and in certain situations “concretely” against it; it all depends o n particular situations. For Con- fucius no general rule can cover each and every unique particular case. If someone invariably sticks t o a general rule, he does not haveyia. There- fore, yia is not only a sensibility; it also has t o be a capacity for judging what is appropriate t o d o in particular situations. As Chung-ying Cheng puts it, “A man of y i a , therefore, must be a man of creative insights who is able t o make appropriate moral judgements in particular situations, judgements which will preserve t h e totality of goodness and j ~ s t i c e . ” ~ ’ b V. TRYING TO DO JUSTICE T O THE PARTICULAR Now let me turn to the particular issue concerning the possibility of doing justice t o the concept of justice in Confucian ethics I mentioned in the introduction. Armed with the Confucian spirit of justice, I think that we may be able t o try t o d o justice t o this particular issue and give a Confucian justification for what we have been doing in this paper. The same issue will arise if I were t o write a paper o n some other topics, say, “the concept of God in Confucian ethics,” or “the concept of individual rights in Confucian ethics,” etc. The list can be endless. So it seems that the question ‘Can we do justice t o the concept of justice in Confucian ethics? ” is just a particular case of a general question of “Can we even talk about Confucian ethics in English without doing injustice to it” or “Can we talk about one culture (or language) in terms of cate- JUSTICE IN CONFUCIAN ETHICS 5 4 1 gories of another different culture (or language) without doing injustice t o it.” One may thus be tempted t o say that we should first solve the general question, Which has to do with translation, interpretation, language and cultural relativism, and then apply tit to our particular case concerning the concept of justice. However, from Confucius, we have learned not t o “cling t o any generality that is independent of concrete reality.”36 With the help from Confucius, we should try t o resist the temptation t o see the whole issue in this way. Confucius and Mencius help us to see that this approach does not do justice t o t h e particular. For it rules out the possibility that all the particular cases, like the gifts offered to Mencius, might not form a homogeneous kind; and, therefore, each of them requires a different treatment. As Confucians have insisted, there might be no abstract genera- lity that can cover each and every particular case. What one can say about “the concept of individual rights in Confucian ethics” may not apply t o “the concept of justice in Confucian ethics.” Nevertheless, it is not easy t o resist the temptation. One may be attracted t o the following approach: one starts with a general theory of language and interpretation, claiming that two languages, in general, can never be translated into each other without doing injustice (or violence) to each of them. The second step is t o apply this general theory t o the particular case of the English term “justice,” concluding that one can never do justice t o the concept of justice in Chinese ethics if one talks about it in English. To utter the English sentence “I am doing justice t o the concept o f justice in Confucian ethics,” according t o this general view of language, would be a performative contradiction. I have argued else- where that this general view of language is problematic, so I will not address the issue here.’9 In fact, 1 do not even need to determine whether this general view is correct. Whether it is correct is irrelevant here. The point is not about the general view itself, but rather, about the approach of solving our problem by regarding it as a particular case of a general view. Another seductive approach is similar in this regard; the difference 5 4 2 YANC X l A O is just that the first step is to decide whether cultural relativism, another general theory, is correct. If it is correct, b y application, we automatical- ly know the answer is ‘‘no” to our particular question “Can we talk about the concept of justice in Confucian ethics in Western-influenced language? ” In the 1970s and ~ O S , there had been a debate about relativism in the English-speaking world?’ It is a vice of the debate that it often remained a t the abstract level. People argued whether relativism in general is true o r false by appealing to some more general theory of language o r theory of understanding (or theory of practice). One can often find discussions conducted in the following abstract way: one assumes two cultures o r languages, A and B, and then, based on some general theory of culture or language, one proceeds t o draw the conclusion that A and B are radically different (‘or similar). Confucius and Mencius, had they known this, would wonder how one can ever know, in such a general way, whether two such abstract things are alike or radically different. In this kind of discussion, a possibility, which particularists are very sensitive t o but strict universalists are not even aware of, was ruled out u priori. The possibility is the following: perhaps two concrete cultures, say, ancient Chinese and ancient Greek are very much alike, whereas ancient Chinese and modern Western cultures are radically different. And, these have to be determined by detailed studies of the two cultures involved. No one in the debate addressed the question at a concrete level, or dealt with any particular cultures or particular concepts in particular cultures. It is their belief that after they get the answer at the general level by philosophical speculation, they can just apply it to the particular cases. However, it should be the other. way around. We should not start with the general questions, but rather, with the particular cultures and particular concept^.^' We must try to d o justice t o the particular and treat different cases differently. Whenever someone talks about cultural relativism, ask him/her ‘With respect to which particular cultures? ” “With respect to which particular concept? ” What follows then should be detailed analysis and comparison of the particular concepts of these 5 4 3 JUSTICE I N CONFUCIAN ETHICS two concrete cultures. This step is unavoidable. Justice requires it?' GRADUATE FACULTY, NEW SCHOOL FOR SOCIAL RESEARCH NOTES 1. This is a much revised version of a paper presented at a panel, organized b y International Society of Chinese Philosophy, on "Confucian Views of Justice" at t h e Eastern Division Meeting, American Philosophical Association (Atlanta, December 2 8 , 1996). I am very grateful t o m y commentator Prof. Chung- ying Cheng for this very helpful comments, which called m y attention t o t h e diversity of uses of t h e term yia in Confucius and Mencius, which led m e to revise t h e paper. I hope Prof. Cheng will agree for t h e better. I have also benefitted from comments by participants a t t h e meeting thanks especially t o Deborah Achtenberg. Xunwu Chen, Lik Kuen Tong. 1 am particularly grateful for Prof. Kwong-loi Shun for taking t h e time t o read t h e early version presented at APA; his comments and critique have helped me to realize that t h e part on t h e relation between Confucian justice and self was not satisfac- tory. I d o not include that part in this version of t h e paper. 1 am indebted t o Prof. Richard Bernstein for teaching me the importance and, perhaps, more importantly, the elusiveness, of phronesis as sensibility to the particular, in a seminar on Gadamer's hermeneutics. I am also grateful t o Ann Dobbs for a conversation with her on Pascal's view on t h e impossibility of justice, which inspired m e t o further revise the paper. Thanks, finally, t o D.D Sun, without whose support, advice, and sense of justice I would n o t have finished this paper 2 . T h e Chinese term chun-rzub has been translated as "the gentleman" "the virtuous man." These patriarchal terms are closer t o t h e actual meanmg. Grammatically speaking, the Chinese characters themselves d o not have gender, but it is clear that by chun-tzu Confucius meant male officials and gentlemen. However, Wte Aristotle's views of justice, Confucian views of justice can still b e useful today. Therefore, I also often try t o include women b YANC XIAO 5 44 3. 4 . 5 . in m y translations b y using terms like "person"; i t is not designed t o cover u p Confucians' injustice t o women. Deborah Achtenberg has convincingly argued that feminist ethics can find resources in Aristotle, w h o is, as she p u t s it, "a paradigmatically sexist thinker," see her "Aristotelian resources for femi- nist thinking," in Feminism and Ancient Philosophy, e d . Julie K. Ward (New York: Routledge, 1996) pp. 95-1 17. Similar arguments can be made with regard t o Confucianism and feminist thinking. It is doing justice t o Confucia- nism if w e are sensitive to its potential uses and possible developments. All quotations from t h e Anulects are t o book and passage numbers in Lun- yu i-chuc, tr. Yung Po-chin (Beijing: Qlung-hua shu-chi, 1980). For example, (7.3) means ' Book 7 Passage 3." I have consulted English transla- tions by D.C Lau, James Legge and Arthur Waley. All q u o t a t i o n s from t h e Mencius are t o book and passage numbers (with book numbers 1A-79 sub- stituted for number 1-14) in Meng-tzu i-chue, tr. Yung P o x h i n d (Beijing: Chung-huu shu-chi, 1 9 8 4 ) For example, (2B: 3) means "Book 2 Passage 3." I have consulted English translations by D.C. Lau, James Legge. Since the references from the Analects and t h e Mencius have different forms, the former having t h e form (7.3) t h e latter (2B:3), I will not indicate t h e Anulects or the Mencius each time. In this paper I shall only focus o n the primary texts, the Analects and t h e Mencius. We find "chen&" and "yia" in t h e Analects and the Mencius, b u t not "cheng y i f . ' * Hsun Tzui is probably the first one who put the two characters together, for example, in chapter 1 3 "On the way of Ministers," Hsin Tzui says, "A tradition expresses my point: 'One should follow t h e Way and not follow the lord.' Thus, if ministers w h o are upright and just ( c h e n g y i ' ) are given posi- tions, then partiality will not characterize t h e court." Hsun-rzui ( 1 3 / 1 9 - 2 0 ) . All references are t o chapter and line number in the H Y ed. I use J o h n Kno- block's three volume translation, Xunzi: A Trunslurion and Study of the Complete Works, vol. 11 (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1990), p. 2 0 0 . d 6 . "The Idea of Social justice in Ancient China," in Sociul justice in rhe Ancienf World, e d . K . D . Irani and Morris Silver (Westport? Greenwood Press, 1 9 9 5 ) . p. 125. 5 4s JUSTICE 1N CONFUCIAN ETHICS 7. 8 . 9 . 10 'Confucian Justice: Achieving a Humane Society," Infernutionul Philosophi- cal Quurterly, Vol. X X X , No. I , March 1990, p. 17. '*Confucian justice," p. 17. However, Heiner Roetz, a German sinologist, has translated y f consistently a s justice, see Heiner Roetz, Confucian Ethics of the Axiul Age (Albany: S t a t e University of New York Press, 1993). But t h e book was published after Peerenboom's 1 9 9 0 paper from which this passage was cited. Nevertheless, in his excellent three volume translation of Xunzi (Hsiin Tzui), J o h n Knoblock has consistently translated yia as justice or social justice. T h e first volume was published in 1988 see Xunzi: A Tmnslu- tion and Study of the Complete Works, vol. 1 (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1988). Peerenboom notices that yia in Hsun Tzui has been o f t e n trans- lated as justice. But he insists that justice may very well b e the most appro- priate translation of yia for Hsun Tzu', b u t n o t for Confucius. T h e question, as he says, then becomes w h a t this tells us a b o u t the difference between t h e philosophy of Hsun Tzui and that of Confucius (ibid., p. 1 7 ) . I shall deal with this question elsewhere. Here let me just say t h a t we have to make t h e distinc- tion between concept and conception, which 1'11 introduce soon, it may be a fact that Hsun Tzu' and Confucius have different conceptions of y? (the difference between their philosophies). b u t this fact should not b e confused with a different claim that they d o n o t even share the same concept ofyia. As I said, I shall deal with the question a b o u t the difference between Hsun Tzul's and Confucius's conceptions of justice elsewhere, Both Lee and Peerenboom carefully avoid drawing such a conclusion. After the passages I cited above, they immediately a d d , respectively, "Practically all discussions that have bearing on t h e issue of justice or social justice are found in the Chinese articulations o n a moral philosophy of political or social order" (Lee, p. 1 2 6 ) . a n d . ' T h i s is not to say that Confucius was not concerned with issues which fall under the rubric of justice understood in a broad sense" (Peerenboom, p. 17) As Amartya Sen puts it, "it is not even clear t o me that Confucius is entirely more authoritarian than Plato or S t . Augustine. I t is true, of course, that many - though n o t all - of the exponents of justice or tolerance or freedom in Asian classical literature tended t o restrict t h e domain of concern to some . . 5 46 YANG XlAO 11. 12. 13. 14. people, excluding others, but that is also true of the ancient West. Aristotle’s exclusion of women and slaves does not make his works on freedom and justice irrelevant to the present-day world We have to see the origin and exposition of ideas in terms of their factored components.” (“Humanity and Citizenship” in For Love of Counny: Debating the Limits of htriotism, ed. Joshua Cohen (Boston: Beacon Press, 1996), p. 118). The sentence “today’s China can be called a Confucian country” is a contro- versial statement I am not making that statement here; what I am making here is a different, conditional one: Given that doday’s China can be called a Confucian country. Governmental spokesmen of several Asian countries such as China and Singa- pore - for example, in the Vienna conference of 1993, to dispute the relevance of human rights in Asia - often make such arguments based on the confusion. This fact is often overlooked or underestimated by Westerners. Here 1 shall only mentioned two examples, one being extremely well-known and one being unknown (especially to outsiders). Let me start with the latter. Since 1988 there has been a “rights-based law movement” in mainland China. I t started with a debate on “What is the basis of law: rights or duty? ” at the First National Conference on Basic Legal Categories held in June 1988. Since then (and even after 1989), there have been many articles focusing on the issue published in magazines and newspapers. The movement criticizes China’s “state-based’’ “duty-based” conaption of law and its te, lency to “one- sidedly emphasize duty.” One of the major spokespersons of the movement says that “individual rights are the basis and goal of the existence of other rights” and that “only a government that takes citizens’ rights seriously can have people’s trust, respect, and obedience to the law. Only a rights-based theory of law can satisfy this need.” This movement is not just an intellectual movement. It is a reflection of the change of Contemporary political-legal culture and popular culture in today’s China. I t also prepared the atmosphere for the 1989 Prodemocratic movement, which is, of course, a much well- known example. 1 have given an argument for this claim in a paper in Chinese: “Rawls’s k Theory of Civil Disobedience and its Chinese version,” Zhe-me ping-lun JUSTICE IN CONFUCIAN ETHICS 547 15. 16. 1 7 . 18. 19. 20. 21. 2 2 . 23. 24. 25. 26. (China Philosophical Review), voL 1, no. 1, (Beijing: Zhongguo-she-huike- x u e Publish House, 1993). (This journal is t h e first independent philosophy journal in China since 1949.) Also see He Huaihong's."On t h e translation of I 'civil disobedience': a reply t o Xiao Yang's critique," Zhong-gueshu-ping (China Book Review), No. 2 , 1994. This j o u r n a l is published in Hong Kong b u t is also distributed in mainland China. I have given a m o r e detailed argument for this claim in "Hegel's t h e o i y of t h e state and civil disobedience," a paper presented in Prof. Agnes Heller's seminar o n Hegel's Philosophy of Right at t h e New School for Social Research in 1994. T h e basic idea is t h a t , since the m o d e r n liberal conception of justice, and that of citizenship, have become historically possible, and even actual in Hegel's sense, in today's China, civil disobedience can t h u s b e justified. See his Shame and Necessity. (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1 9 9 3 ) ; see, for example, p. 166. Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1985), p. 165. Also see his easy ' T h e T r u t h in relativism" in Moral Luck. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1 9 8 1 ) , pp. 132-143. These words are Ronald Dworkin's, Law's Empire, (Cambrdige: Harvard Uni- versity Press, 1986). p. 7 0 . He also gives a more articulated account of the distinction, see especially pp. 46-53, 70-76. A Theory o f h s r i c e . (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 197 I ) , p. 5 . Ethics and the Limits o f Philosophy. p. 1 6 5 . Ethicsand the Limits o f P h i l o s o p h y , pp. 1 6 5 6 . Gregory Vlastos, "Justice and Happiness in t h e Republic': Pluto: A Collection of Critical Essayr, vol. 11, ed. Gregory Vlastos (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1978), p. 66. A Theory of Justice. pp. 10-1 1. Political Liberalism, papcrback, (New York: Columbia University Press, 1 9 9 6 ) . p. 14, n. 15. I intentionally include "a wife," so this formulation cf the concept o f j u s t i c e will be broad enough to be also shared by a sexist conception of justice; see (6B: 1 ) in the Mencius Neverthelss, it seems that Rawls would agree that a concept of justice need 548 YANG XIAO not have these features. At o n e point, h e says that Aristotle's definition of justice is framed t o apply t o actions and persons, whereas t h e definition of justice he a d o p t s "is designed t o apply directly t o the m o s t important case, the justice of t h e basic structure." But, right after this, he says, ' T h e r e is n o conflict with t h e traditional notion." T h e term "notion" here obviously means "concept." T o p u t it in other words, Rawls and Aristotle share t h e same concept or n o t i o n o f justice; see A Theory of Iwn'ce, p. 11. 1 shall n o t use t h e modified formulation of Rawls s in this paper. However, it will b e a very useful o n e when w e want to know w h a t A r u t o t l e or Confucius would say a b o u t t h e basic structure of a society and whether their views of justice are comparable with liberalism. Rawls acknowledges this, see A Theory ofJurtice, p. 5 . "Cases" d o n o t have t o b e limited t o 'human beings", so I add "situations" t o make t h e concept a really broad one. The Concept o f k w . (Oxford. Oxford University Press, 196 I ) , p. 1 5 5 . Mengrzu fui.chieh-luo (Taipei: T'ai-wan shang-wu yin-shu-kuan, 1 9 8 0 ) , pp. 2 1 . 2 8 . 29. 30. 4168. 31. For those w h o believe in the last option, this classification very likely would remind them of a passage in Jorge Luis Borges, which later has become well- known since Michel Foucault started his book The Order of Things with this passage and claimed t h a t his book first arose o u t of it. This passage q u o t e s a certain Chinese encyclopedia in which it is written that animals a r e classified into: a) belonging t o t h e Emperor, b ) embalmed, c) t a m e , d ) sucking pigs, e) sirens, f) fabulous, g) stray dogs, h) included in the present classification, i ) frenzied, j) innumerable, k) drawn with a very fine Lamelhair brush, I ) et ceferu, m ) having just broken the water pitcher, n) that from a long way off look like fhes. Like o t h e r things about China Borges "describes" in his short stories, this o n e is also his invention. Foucault w a n t s to use this exotic inven- tion of classic China for purposes that have to d o with challenging Western classifications. This raises complicated issues, such as, whether it is doing justice t o classic China when the invention in its name is being used as means for ends other than furthering better and more' balanced understandings of classic China. But I can t go into these issues here. JUSTICE IN CONFUCIAN ETHICS 5 4 9 32. For a detailed analysis of t h e other uses of via, such a s those that have to d o with t h e sense of honor and shame, and t h a t have to d o with ria as being internal, see Kwong-loi Shun, Mencius und Early Chinese Thoughf (Stunford: Stanford University Press, 1997). There is a tension between yia as being internal and ria as being just to the particular. It is almost impossible t o hold these t w o uses together. I shall try t o show how Mencius does i t elsewhere. Except in 3B:4 and 4.5, where Mencius and Confucius d o n o t use yia b u t toop instead. What they ask is: “Is it in accordance with toop ( t h e way or principle) to t a k e g?” However, toop and yia are tightly related and probably refer to the same thing. In 7.16 and 4.5, Confucius uses ya a n d tuop in a similar way: each eta in 7.16 and mop in 4.5) is said to b e a principle accor- ding t o which o n e determines whether o n e should t a k e or gain wealth and rank. More importantly, for Mencius and Confucius, t h e metaphor for yia is always tuop ( “ t h e way” or “path”) see 5 A : 7 , 4A.10, 6 A : l l , 7A:33, 4B:2. In fact. with regard t o Mencius’s saying in 4B:2, “ [ T h e great m a n ] walks in the great tuop of t h e world,” Chu Hsiq makes the following comment: ‘“The great tuop isyia.*’ Here I follow Chung-ying Cheng (“On ria as a universal principle of specific application in Confucian morality,” in his New Dimensions of Confuciunisrn a n d Neo-Confuciun Philosophy, Albany: S t a t e University of New York Press, 1991, pp. 2 3 3 4 5 ) , and David L. Hall and Roger T. Ames (Thinking Through Confucius, Albany: State University of New Y o r k Press, 1987, pp. 101-2). However, 1 think that Hall and Ames have gone too far in saying that we should n o t use t h e term “principle o/yia” at all; their reason is the following: “More o f t e n t h a n not. this entails t h e assumption, tacit or explicit, that such principles are transcendently grounded” (p. 101). B u t , as the phrase “more often than n o t ” alsoindicates, to use the term “principle” does n o t necessarily entail t h e assumption, just like the term “justice” does not necessarily entail t h e conception o f equal rights. From t h e nature o f confrontation between him and Mencius in other passages (7B:23 we may also include 2B:lO and 5B: 14, if we agree w i t h Chao Ch’is that Ch’en Tzu’ in these two passages is Ch’en Chen’), I suspect that he is probably not Mencius’s disciple. Especially, judged from his position, very 33. 34 35. 550 YANG XlAO likely he is a Mohist. Or, if he is a disciple, he is, a t least, influenced by Mohism’s universalism regarding the principle of ria; also see my next note. Here I do not have space to show that it also satisfiesanother version of (Y), i.e., (Y) which is formulated in terms of leim (see my section 111 above). In fact, it is not difficult to show that this is the case. In 3B:lO and 5B 4 , Mencius himself speaks of ya in terms of leim. The way to understand these passages is that we must take seriously the fact that the debate recorded in these passages is a debate between Mencius and Mohists and that they use the logical term leim in the way it is used in Mohist logical texts, which is available to us. This is crucial, because Mencius does not leave us any logical text, although he appears to be very good at it. It seems that leim is a logical term commonly used by Mohists, Mencius and other carlier thinkers (e.g., Hsin Tzu’). This paper is part of a larger project which will show that the Mencius as a whole can be better understood within the framework sketched in this paper. Some very difficult passages. such as3B:lO,SB:4,2B:8,7B:2, 1B:8, 3 8 5 , etc. in the Menchrs can be better interpreted. The project also shows that yia is used in the way sketched here in other early Chinese texts. New Dimensions of Confucian and Neo-Confucian Philosophy (Albany: State University of New York Press, 19911, p. 236. New Dimensions of Confucian and Neo-Confucian Philosophy. pp. 236-1. Derrida seems to be endorsing such a general view, for a critique of it, see my paper “Justice and Interpretation: A Wittgensteinian critique of Derrida’s Force of Law”’, which was presented in Prof. Albrecht Wellmer and Prof. Ruth Sonderegger’s seminar ’Toward a critique of Hermeneutic reason’’ at the New School for Social Research in 1995. Derrida’s essay was first publish- ed in Cardozo Luw Review, vol. 11, 1990. It was reprinted in Deconstruction und rhe Possibiliry of Jusn’ce, ed. Drucilla Cornell, Michel Rosenfeld and David Gray Carlson (New York Routledge, 1992). Some of the important papers on the issue can be found in Rufionulify and Relufivisrn, ed. Martin Hollis and Steven Lukes (Oxford: Blackwell, 1982). There are also quite a few books on the issue the literature is massive. I owe this point to Prof. Richard Bernstein. 1 am also grateful to him for encouraging me to explore the issue in Confucian ethics. As he pointed out 36. 31. 38. 39. 40. 41. JUSTICE IN CONFUCIAN ETHICS 55 1 to m e in an unforgettable conversation, t h e debate about relativism has to move to the particular level; and, furthermore, every move is predictable o r has already been made at t h e abstract level. However, I am also aware that these claims are still abstract. T h e slogan “Do justice t o t h e particular,” like all the other slogans such as “Putting immedi- ately into practice what o n e has learned,” i s j u s t another general, abstract and empty rule. T h e slogan can push people t o t h e opposite of w h a t it says. It can negates itself and be carried to extreme - that is, a n abstract relativism, which, for example, may claim that Chinese culture, as a particular, is totally different from Western culture and cannot b e characterized by a n y Western categories. What David Nivison says a b o u t the virtue of “moderation” or t h e “mean” also applies t o t h e virtue of “justice” o r “sensibility to t h e p a r t i c u k r ” . ‘It would seem that if w e give t h e notion of t h e mean any posi- tive content, w e can imagine a situation in which it negates itself, at a higher (or lower) level: even moderation can be carried to extremes.” (“Replies and Comments,” in Chinese Lonyage, Thought, and Culture: Nivison and his Cn’dcr, e d . Philip 1. Ivanhoe, Chicago: Open Court, 1996, p. 291). 42. CHINESE GL OSSAR Y work_jlpk7rha3bfkdlxceazqez5ga4 ---- Procedural Justice as Autonomy Regulation Jan-Willem van Prooijen VU University Amsterdam The present research investigated the relation between autonomy (i.e., freedom of choice) and procedural justice. Three studies tested the hypothesis that people would be particularly sensitive to the fairness of decision-making procedures when they experience deprivation of autonomy needs. Study 1 indicated that procedural justice judgments indeed were influenced more strongly by variations in decision-making procedures among participants who experienced little autonomy in their life. In Study 2, these findings were conceptually replicated by manipulating whether participants were provided with choice on an issue that was unrelated to the outcomes of the subsequent decision-making process. Study 3 revealed evidence for the hypothesis in a field setting. It is concluded that procedural justice is functional to regulate basic autonomy needs. Keywords: procedural justice, autonomy, self-determination, fairness, basic psychological needs In contemporary democratic societies, freedom of choice is considered to be an invaluable aspect of human well-being. People desire a sense of freedom in virtually all life domains and resent the feeling of being pressured into unwanted thoughts or behav- iors. The extent to which people feel free to make their own choices and experience a sense of volition in their actions is referred to as people’s sense of autonomy. Autonomy is a central construct in self-determination theory, which has emphasized the beneficial consequences of experiencing freedom of choice on various dimensions (Deci & Ryan, 1985, 2000). This theory asserts that autonomy is one of the three most basic psychological needs, the other two needs being relatedness (cf. Baumeister & Leary, 1995) and competence (Sheldon, Ryan, & Reis, 1996). These needs are defined as innate psychological necessities that must be satisfied to ensure ongoing mental health, psychological growth, and optimal functioning. In correspondence with this, autonomy has been argued and found to be associated with intrinsic motiva- tion (Deci, Koestner, & Ryan, 1999; Zuckerman, Porac, Lathin, Smith, & Deci, 1978), persistence (Moller, Deci, & Ryan, 2006), goal attainment (Sheldon & Elliot, 1998), and a general increase in subjective well-being (Reis, Sheldon, Gable, Roscoe, & Ryan, 2000; Sheldon, Ryan, Deci, & Kasser, 2004). Likewise, depriva- tion of autonomy needs can have a variety of detrimental conse- quences such as apathy and alienation (for an overview, see Deci & Ryan, 2002). The extent to which people’s autonomy needs are satisfied depends in part on contextual factors such as the extent to which the direct social environment is supportive of autonomy. This implies that external factors can potentially thwart people’s auton- omy needs, and hence, it makes sense that people are concerned about the development of protective mechanisms that help to buffer against autonomy threats. One such protective mechanism that has been developed by society is the enforcement of moral norms, as moral norms regulate social behavior such that extreme threats to autonomy (e.g., imposing harm) are constrained (Folger, 2001; cf. Rozin, Lowery, Imada, & Haidt, 1999). This autonomy- protective function of moral norms contains a paradox: Moral norms constitute obligations of appropriate conduct, thereby de- creasing choice with regard to what behavior is considered accept- able. This paradox was already observed by classic philosophers such as Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1762; Cranston, 1968) and Cesare Beccaria (1764; Paolucci, 1963), who noted that people desire a social contract in which they agree to give up some of their own individual freedoms by developing norms that prescribe what behaviors toward others are unacceptable in order to ensure overall security and happiness. Likewise, Folger (2001) noted that most people prefer a state of “bounded autonomy” in which people’s freedom of choice is protected, but at the same time also restricted, by moral obligations to respect other people’s autonomy and well-being. Such collective autonomy protection either succeeds or fails depending on the extent to which others also take these moral obligations seriously. The expectation that others adhere to their moral obligations becomes particularly relevant when interacting with a more pow- erful individual who is in a position to legitimately exert influence on the autonomy that one experiences. For instance, decision- making authorities often develop policies and rules that dictate what kind of behaviors their subordinates are required to display, raising concerns about autonomy in interactions with these author- ities (cf. Van den Bos & Lind, 2002; Van den Bos, Wilke, & Lind, 1998; Van Prooijen, Van den Bos, & Wilke, 2007). Likewise, it has been noted that leaders often are able to exploit followers, and hence, followers are more willing to accept leadership when they can exercise some form of control over leaders to minimize the potential for these autonomy threats (Boehm, 1999; Van Vugt, I thank Romy van der Lee for her assistance in collecting the data of Study 1 and Intan Samsuria and Marije Bun for all their invaluable efforts in preparing and conducting Study 3. Furthermore, I thank Caryl Rusbult, Paul van Lange, Catrin Finkenauer, Monique Pollmann, Joel Vuolevi, Francesca Righetti, and Kaska Kubacka for their helpful comments on a previous draft of the manuscript. Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to Jan- Willem van Prooijen, Department of Social Psychology, VU University Amsterdam, Van der Boechorststraat 1, 1081 BT Amsterdam, the Nether- lands. E-mail: jw.van.prooijen@psy.vu.nl Journal of Personality and Social Psychology © 2009 American Psychological Association 2009, Vol. 96, No. 6, 1166 –1180 0022-3514/09/$12.00 DOI: 10.1037/a0014153 1166 Hogan, & Kaiser, 2008). These considerations suggest that subor- dinates are concerned about the extent to which authorities will respect their basic autonomy needs. One possible way for author- ities to address these concerns is to adhere to their moral obliga- tions by implementing fair decision-making procedures that ensure the rights and dignity of subordinates. The extent to which people feel treated fairly by authorities during a decision-making process is referred to as procedural justice (Thibaut & Walker, 1975). Accumulating research indicates that people assign much value to procedural justice, which is reflected in findings that fair decision- making procedures influence a wide range of human perceptions, emotions, and behaviors, and do so across diverse social settings. For instance, procedural justice has been found to increase feelings of being respected, the extent to which subordinates identify with the institutions that the authority represents, and subordinates’ willingness to voluntarily display behaviors that benefit these institutions (for overviews, see Brockner & Wiesenfeld, 1996; Cropanzano, Byrne, Bobocel, & Rupp, 2001; De Cremer & Tyler, 2005; Folger & Cropanzano, 1998; Lind & Tyler, 1988; Tyler & Blader, 2000, 2003; Tyler & Lind, 1992; Van den Bos & Lind, 2002). Although such a relation between autonomy needs and proce- dural justice may seem plausible, empirical research hitherto has failed to investigate this assumed relation in a satisfactory way. In the present article, I examined the possibility that procedural justice is in fundamental ways related to people’s need for auton- omy. As such, I pursued two interrelated goals. First, the present work integrates insights derived from self-determination theory with existing knowledge on procedural justice. In particular, I investigate whether people try to regulate their basic autonomy needs by attending to the fairness of decision-making procedures. Hence, the studies presented here were designed to make a novel contribution by investigating to what extent satisfaction or depri- vation of autonomy needs have implications for people’s fairness- based responses to decision-making procedures. Second, the present research proffers a novel answer to the question of why people care about fair decision-making procedures. For the last three decades, scientists have stressed the importance of under- standing why procedural justice matters to people, but the role of autonomy needs has been largely ignored or overlooked in con- temporary procedural justice research (e.g., De Cremer & Tyler, 2005; Folger & Cropanzano, 1998; Lind & Tyler, 1988; Thibaut & Walker, 1975; Tyler & Blader, 2003; Tyler & Lind, 1992; Van den Bos & Lind, 2002). I propose that the question of why procedural justice matters cannot be answered in full without taking human autonomy needs into account. In the following, I lay out my line of reasoning in more detail and introduce the specifics of the present research. Procedural Justice and Autonomy To determine whether procedures are fair or unfair, people evaluate procedures by means of various criteria. Leventhal (1980) summarized the most prominent of these criteria by postulating that for people to feel treated fairly during a decision-making process, the procedures should (for instance) be consistent between persons, should make accurate use of available information, should be compatible with fundamental moral and ethical values, and should be representative of the basic concerns and values of the parties affected by the decision. These criteria are related to a variety of procedural justice phenomena that have been studied extensively in empirical research. An illustration of a typical procedural justice phenomenon can be found in the effects of voice: People tend to feel that they have been treated fairer following decision-making procedures that allow them an oppor- tunity to voice their opinion as compared with procedures that deny them such an opportunity (Folger, 1977; Folger, Rosenfield, Grove, & Corkran, 1979). Opportunities for voice are considered important for various reasons: For instance, voice opportunities raise outcome expectancies (cf. Houlden, LaTour, Walker, & Thibaut, 1978; Thibaut & Walker, 1975) and communicate posi- tive relational information, such as being respected and appreci- ated as a valuable member of one’s community (e.g., Tyler, 1987; Tyler & Lind, 1992). Voice effects are robust and generalize across methods and samples (Brockner et al., 1998; Folger et al., 1979; Lind, Kanfer, & Earley, 1990; Van den Bos, 2003; Van den Bos et al., 1998; Van Prooijen, Karremans, & Van Beest, 2006; Van Prooijen, Van den Bos, & Wilke, 2004, 2005). Early interpretations of procedural justice phenomena such as the voice effect emphasized that fair procedures support a feeling of control over the decision-making process. In particular, a line of research instigated by Thibaut and Walker (1975) indicated that control over the outcome in a dispute resolution setting (decision control) and control over the way the evidence is presented (pro- cess control) exert independent effects on litigants’ reactions to the decision-making process (e.g., Houlden et al., 1978; Thibaut & Walker, 1975). In everyday life, however, people often have to leave ultimate control over the final decision to decision-making authorities. It has therefore been assumed that people desire pro- cess control because this might enable them to influence the final decisions. This line of reasoning has been referred to as the “instrumental” perspective, in that its basic proposition is that people value fair procedures (such as voice procedures) because these procedures may enable them to influence the specific out- come of a decision-making process. Given that instrumental per- spectives assign a central role to control in procedural justice judgments, it may well be that these perspectives are informative about the relation between autonomy and procedural justice. As such, it is important to note that classic instrumental perspectives are insufficient to fully appreciate the role of autonomy needs in the psychology of procedural justice. In particular, the core as- sumptions of instrumental perspectives restrict people’s desire for control to an attempt of influencing the specific outcome that happens to be at stake in the decision-making process. This focus on control over the immediate outcomes of procedures is concep- tually too narrow because it ignores the possibility that procedural justice judgments emerge from a more general desire to address basic autonomy needs. During interactions with decision-making authorities, people have reason to believe that their basic autonomy needs are at stake because authorities often are in the position to pressure recipients into a wide variety of unwanted outcomes, situations, or actions. Such an asymmetrical interdependence structure between au- thority and recipients is related to a situation that has been referred to as the “fundamental social dilemma” (Van den Bos et al., 1998; cf. Komorita & Parks, 1994): People often are concerned about the question of whether they can trust others not to take advantage of them. This question is particularly salient when interacting with 1167AUTONOMY AND PROCEDURAL JUSTICE authorities, as these authorities often have the power to cause harm by exploiting a recipient or by excluding a recipient from valuable social relationships. Hence, recipients are in many ways vulnerable to coercion exercised by the authority, potentially threatening basic autonomy needs. This fundamental social dilemma constitutes the basis of social-cognitive procedural justice theories such as fair- ness heuristic theory (Lind, Kulik, Ambrose, & De Vera-Park, 1993; Van den Bos et al., 1998) and the related uncertainty management model (Van den Bos, 2001; Van den Bos & Lind, 2002). According to these theories, people use procedural justice information to psychologically resolve the problems they have in their interactions with authorities because fair or unfair procedures are informative about the extent to which the authority’s intentions are benevolent. By derivation, it may therefore be argued that procedural justice is functional for people to gauge the extent to which their autonomy needs are threatened. If a decision-making authority treats recipients in a fair way, for instance by granting them the opportunity to voice an opinion, then recipients may infer that the authority has the intention to support their autonomy instead of forcing them into an unwanted situation through coer- cion. If an authority treats recipients in an unfair way, for instance by denying them an opportunity to voice an opinion, then recipi- ents may infer that the authority is not autonomy supportive but rather seeks to impose decisions upon them. In summary, recipi- ents are likely to interpret fair versus unfair decision-making procedures as evidence that the authority has the intention to support versus undermine their basic autonomy needs. The Present Research In the present research, I tested novel predictions that bridge insights from self-determination theory (Deci & Ryan, 1985, 2000) and insights from procedural justice theories (Lind et al., 1993; Van den Bos & Lind, 2002). On the basis of the theoretical framework described above, it is assumed that autonomy and procedural justice are related in fundamental ways, as procedural justice is expected to be functional for the regulation of basic autonomy needs. My line of reasoning is rooted in self- determination theory’s core proposition that autonomy is a basic psychological need that is essential for optimal psychological functioning. Traditionally, the majority of self-determination re- search focused on the consequences of autonomy need satisfaction for well-being, performance, and intrinsic motivation in goal pur- suit (e.g., Deci et al., 1999; Reis et al., 2000; Sheldon et al., 2004). It has also been noted, however, that people actively seek satis- faction of autonomy needs when this need has been thwarted. Notably, Deci and Ryan (2000) proposed that equifinality is a basic property of autonomy needs, which means that “people are persistent in their attempts to satisfy primary needs, devising new paths when old routes no longer work” (p. 248). This notion corresponds to a related body of literature, in which it has been argued that people display reactance when they are deprived of autonomy: People try to regain a sense of freedom when their freedom has been threatened (Brehm & Brehm, 1981). As such, the need for autonomy is regarded as a psychological necessity that continuously needs to be maintained above a minimum level, and people actively seek opportunities in their social environment to compensate for autonomy deprivation. This compensatory response to autonomy deficiencies has im- plications for potential differences between people who experience deprivation of autonomy needs versus people whose autonomy needs are satisfied. People can experience deprivations of auton- omy both structurally (e.g., being low in trait autonomy; i.e., individual differences in the perception of freedom of choice) and situationally (e.g., being denied choice in a particular situation). It can be inferred that if individuals experience deprivation of au- tonomy, either structurally or situationally, then they are relatively sensitive to autonomy-related cues in their direct social environ- ment. Such cues may provide opportunities for autonomy regula- tion: Messages that support one’s autonomy help an individual to repair or reconfirm a satisfactory sense of volitional functioning, but messages that threaten one’s autonomy may instigate even further moral indignation as people are explicitly denied the op- portunity to compensate for autonomy deficiencies. If people’s autonomy needs are satisfied, however, then they are less likely to be sensitive to autonomy-related cues in their direct social envi- ronment, as there is no incentive to engage in compensation- seeking behavior. In other words, there is not much urgency to regulate the need for autonomy when this need is already fulfilled above a satisfactory level. Such autonomy-related cues may be found in the quality of the decision-making procedures that are adopted by authorities. Build- ing on the argument that the perceived fairness of decision-making procedures is informative about the extent to which an authority has the intention to behave in ways that are supportive of auton- omy (cf. Lind et al., 1993; Van den Bos & Lind, 2002; Van den Bos et al., 1998), I suggest that people attend to the fairness of decision-making procedures more strongly when they experience some deprivation of basic autonomy needs. Importantly, the present line of reasoning would suggest that such increased sen- sitivity to procedural justice is likely to be found even when the source of autonomy deprivation is unrelated to the specific out- comes of the decision-making process. Autonomy is assumed to be a basic psychological need that, when thwarted, may be replen- ished by providing people with a sense of volition in a seemingly unrelated domain (Deci & Ryan, 2000). Furthermore, procedural justice is assumed to address basic autonomy needs beyond a sense of control over the specific outcomes of the decision-making process. Combining these arguments leads to the prediction that fairness-based responses are increasingly sensitive to decision- making procedures to the extent that recipients (a) structurally experience little choice in their life or (b) recently have been denied choice in a domain that is unrelated to the expected outcomes of the decision-making process. Thus, the general hypothesis to be tested in the present research is that people’s fairness-based responses are more sensitive to variations in decision-making procedures when they experience deprivation of autonomy as opposed to when their autonomy needs are fulfilled (Hypothesis 1). This hypothesis was tested in two laboratory experiments (Studies 1 and 2) and one field study (Study 3). Study 1 The first study was a laboratory experiment in which trait autonomy was measured as an individual-difference variable: Par- ticipants responded to a validated scale that is designed to assess the extent to which people experience a sense of choice in their life 1168 VAN PROOIJEN (Sheldon, 1995; Sheldon et al., 1996). Low scores on this scale reflect that participants feel structurally deprived of autonomy, in that participants do not experience much choice in their everyday activities. Furthermore, participants encountered a manipulation of a decision-making procedure in the context of a validated exper- imental procedure in which variations in procedural justice phe- nomena are investigated. In this procedure, the experimenter either grants versus denies participants an opportunity to voice their opinions about the number of lottery tickets that should be as- signed to the participant (Van den Bos, 2001; Van den Bos & Van Prooijen, 2001; Van den Bos et al., 1998; Van Prooijen, Karre- mans, & Van Beest, 2006; Van Prooijen et al., 2004). The main dependent variables constituted participants’ procedural justice judgments, that is, evaluations of how fairly they felt that they were treated by the experimenter.1 On the basis of the current line of reasoning, it was expected that procedural justice judgments would be influenced more strongly by the manipulation of voice versus no-voice procedures among participants who scored low as opposed to high in trait autonomy. Method Participants and design. A total of 90 participants (35 men, 55 women; mean age � 21.23, SD � 3.73) were recruited via flyers that were distributed in the VU University’s student cafeterias. The hypothesis was tested in a design in which trait autonomy was measured as a continuous independent variable, and procedure was manipulated by randomly assigning participants to voice versus no-voice conditions. The study was conducted simultaneously with two other unrelated studies. The studies lasted approximately 60 min, and participants were paid 7 Euros (approximately $9.50 U.S.) for their participation. Procedure. Upon arrival at the laboratory, participants were seated in separate cubicles. Inside the cubicles, participants found computer equipment that was used to present the stimulus infor- mation and to register the data. Participants were informed that they would take part in several unrelated studies. Participants then began with “Experiment 1,” which was presented as a study of life experiences. This study comprised various questionnaires. To measure trait autonomy, participants completed the Choicefulness subscale of the Self Determination Scale (Sheldon, 1995; Sheldon et al., 1996). This five-item scale is designed to measure the extent to which participants experience a sense of choice with respect to their behavior. Each item of the scale presents participants with two opposing statements, and participants are asked to indicate which of the statements feels most true for them. An example item is “I always feel like I choose the things I do” (Statement A) versus “I sometimes feel that it’s not really me choosing the things I do” (Statement B) (1 � only A feels true; 7 � only B feels true). Participants’ answers to the items were coded such that low scores indicate experienced choice deprivation, and high scores indicate a strong sense of choice. The items were averaged into a reliable autonomy scale (� � .84; M � 5.58, SD � 1.08). After completion of the questionnaire, participants continued with “Experiment 2,” which was presented as an unrelated study concerning how people perform tasks. Participants were led to believe that all computers in the lab were connected and that the experimenter (who was allegedly in one of the other cubicles) could send computer messages to all participants during the ex- periment (in reality, all stimulus information was preprogrammed). Participants were informed that a lottery with a prize of 50 Euros (approximately $68 U.S.) would take place among all participants and that following the tasks, the experimenter would allocate some number of lottery tickets to participants (e.g., Van den Bos, 2001, 2003; Van den Bos et al., 1998; Van Prooijen, De Cremer, et al., 2008; Van Prooijen, Karremans, & Van Beest, 2006; Van Prooijen et al., 2004, 2007). Participants then continued with the tasks, which entailed count- ing squares within larger figures (for a detailed description of the tasks, see Van den Bos & Van Prooijen, 2001; Van den Bos et al., 1998; Van Prooijen, Van den Bos, & Wilke, 2002). Participants were instructed to complete as many tasks as possible within 3 min. Following the tasks, the procedure manipulation was induced. Participants in the voice condition were informed that they were allowed an opportunity to voice their opinion about the number of lottery tickets that they thought should be allocated to them. These participants were then asked to type in the number of lottery tickets they believed they should receive. Participants in the no-voice condition were informed that they were not allowed an opportunity to voice their opinion about the number of lottery tickets that they thought should be allocated to them. These participants were not asked to type in the number of lottery tickets they believed they should receive. All participants were then informed that they would receive their lottery tickets at the end of the experiment and that they first would be asked a number of questions. These questions pertained to the dependent variables and manipulation checks. To measure perceived procedural justice, participants were asked the following three questions: “How fair was the way you were treated by the experimenter?” (1 � very unfair, 7 � very fair), “How correct were you treated by the experimenter?” (1 � very incorrect, 7 � very correct), and “How respectful were you treated by the experimenter?” (1 � not respectful, 7 � very respectful). These three items were averaged into a reliable pro- cedural justice scale (� � .81). To check the procedure manipu- lation, participants responded to the following two questions (1 � not at all, 7 � very much): “To what extent did the experimenter allow you an opportunity to voice your opinion about the number 1 There is an ongoing debate concerning terminology for the perceived fairness of interpersonal treatment. Organizational justice scholars have argued that procedural justice should refer only to the perceived fairness of the formal decision-making structure and that the perceived fairness of treatment should be referred to as interactional justice (e.g., Bies & Moag, 1986; Colquitt, 2001). Other justice scholars, however, have argued that treatment quality is a necessary component of procedural justice judg- ments, as people attend to both formal decision-making procedures as well as to the quality of interpersonal treatment to evaluate procedural justice (e.g., Tyler & Blader, 2003). In the present article, I adopt the latter (more generalized) terminology. I believe that explicitly distinguishing between procedural and interactional justice makes sense only in organizational settings where there is a formalized decision-making structure and contin- uous interaction with authorities, enabling people to evaluate formal decision-making procedures separately from their interpersonal contact with the direct supervisor. In situations wherein people interact with a decision maker only once (as in Studies 1 and 2), it is in all likelihood much more difficult for recipients to view the formal decision-making process (e.g., being granted vs. denied voice) separately from the quality of interpersonal treatment. 1169AUTONOMY AND PROCEDURAL JUSTICE of lottery tickets that should be allocated to you?” and “How much attention did the experimenter have for your opinion about the number of lottery tickets that should be allocated to you?” These two items were averaged into a reliable procedure check scale (� � .83). After this, participants were debriefed, thanked, and paid for their participation. Results The results were analyzed with hierarchical regression analyses that specified the main effects of autonomy and procedure in Step 1 and the interaction in Step 2. Participants’ scores on the auton- omy scale were centered, and the conditions of the procedure manipulation were effect coded (1 for the voice condition, �1 for the no-voice condition). The interaction term was based on the product of the centered autonomy scale and the effect-coded procedure manipulation (Cohen, Cohen, West, & Aiken, 2003). Manipulation check. The regression analysis on the procedure check scale indicated that only Step 1 accounted for a significant part of the variance (R2 � .61), F(2, 87) � 69.02, p � .001. Results revealed a significant procedure main effect (� � .78, p � .001). Participants in the voice condition perceived more opportu- nities to voice their opinion (M � 5.01, SD � 1.23) than partici- pants in the no-voice condition (M � 1.91, SD � 1.26). These results suggest that participants perceived the procedure manipu- lation as intended. Procedural justice judgments. The analysis of participants’ procedural justice judgments indicated that Step 1 accounted for a significant portion of the variance (R2 � .15), F(2, 87) � 7.91, p � .01. The procedure main effect was significant (� � .39, p � .001), indicating that participants in the voice condition felt that they were treated more fairly by the experimenter (M � 4.64, SD � 1.42) than were participants in the no-voice condition (M � 3.50, SD � 1.31). More important was the finding that Step 2 was significant (�R2 � .04), F(1, 86) � 4.06, p � .05, yielding the predicted interaction term (� � �.20, p � .05). The Autonomy � Procedure interaction is displayed graphically in Figure 1. To examine the specific nature of this interaction, I conducted simple slopes analyses. In correspondence with the hypothesis, the procedure manipulation exerted a stronger effect among participants who scored low in trait autonomy (� � .56, p � .002) than among participants who scored high in trait autonomy (� � .30, p � .03). These findings support the predic- tion that people’s procedural justice judgments are more sensitive to variations in decision-making procedures to the extent that they feel less autonomous in life. In addition, it may be noted that trait autonomy did not predict procedural justice judgments among participants in the voice con- dition (� � �.26, p � .08) or among participants in the no-voice condition (� � .15, p � .32). These latter findings suggest that both the voice and no-voice conditions contributed to the emer- gence of an interaction and underscore that the interaction should be interpreted in terms of the influence of trait autonomy on the relative magnitude of the effects of voice versus no-voice proce- dures. Discussion Study 1 provided preliminary evidence for the hypothesis that variations in decision-making procedures exert a stronger impact on procedural justice judgments among people who experience little as opposed to a lot of choice in their life. A remarkable aspect of this finding is that the trait autonomy scale (Sheldon, 1995; Sheldon et al., 1996) tapped experiences in participants’ lives in general, and hence, the scale was fully unrelated to the procedure manipulation and to the specific decision regarding the distribution of lottery tickets. This supports the assertion that autonomy depri- vation increases people’s sensitivity to decision-making proce- dures, even when the source of autonomy deprivation is unrelated to the expected outcomes of the decision-making process. The present findings are in correspondence with the idea that people regulate their basic autonomy needs by attending to the fairness of treatment by decision makers. Although promising, the present findings need to be complemented and extended in a second experiment. Instead of measuring autonomy as an individual- difference variable, in Study 2 autonomy was manipulated by providing versus not providing participants with choice regarding an issue that was unrelated to the outcome of the subsequent decision-making procedure. Study 2 By experimentally manipulating autonomy, Study 2 was de- signed to extend Study 1 by providing more conclusive evidence for the empirical relation that is under investigation here. Partici- pants responded to a modification of the experimental paradigm of Study 1. The study was again presented as a study on performing tasks. Autonomy was manipulated by providing versus not pro- viding participants with a choice opportunity regarding what kind of task they would perform (cf. Moller et al., 2006). In addition, a control condition was included in which participants were not made aware of choice possibilities. Then, the procedure manipu- lation was induced orthogonally from the autonomy manipulation: Participants were granted versus denied an opportunity to voice their opinion regarding a decision about how to divide lottery tickets. The main dependent variables again were participants’ procedural justice judgments. It was expected that procedural justice judgments would be influenced more strongly by the ma- nipulation of voice versus no-voice procedures among participants in the no-choice condition in comparison to participants in the choice condition. 2 3 4 5 6 Low High Trait autonomy Voice procedure No-voice procedure Figure 1. Participants’ procedural justice judgments as a function of trait autonomy and procedure in Study 1. 1170 VAN PROOIJEN Method Participants and design. The hypothesis was tested in a 3 (autonomy: choice versus no choice versus control) � 2 (proce- dure: voice versus no voice) factorial design. A total of 108 participants (32 men, 76 women; mean age � 20.58; SD � 2.62) were recruited via flyers that were distributed in the VU Univer- sity’s student cafeterias. Participants were assigned randomly to one of the six experimental conditions. The study was followed by another unrelated study. Together the studies lasted approximately 30 min, and participants received 3.50 Euros (approximately $4.75 U.S.) for their participation. Procedure. The experiment took place in the same laboratory as in Study 1. The introduction to the study was the same as the “Experiment 2” portion of Study 1. Before starting with the tasks, the autonomy manipulation was administered. In the choice con- dition, participants were informed that they would perform one out of two possible tasks: a “contrast sensitivity task” or an “intuitive decision task.” Participants were informed that, in general, people tend to evaluate both tasks as equally positive. Furthermore, both tasks were described as equally difficult and time-consuming. Participants were then allowed to choose which task they would perform. In the no-choice condition, participants received the same introduction. However, these participants were informed that they would be assigned to the contrast sensitivity task. In the control condition, no mention of two tasks was made. Participants in this condition were informed that all participants would be performing a contrast sensitivity task. This condition differed from the other two conditions in that no choice opportunities were made salient to the participants. Participants then proceeded with the task. The actual task was the same for all participants.2 During the task, a checker-board figure appeared on the computer screen for 10 s. Each figure contained black and white squares that were arranged in a random pattern. After 10 s, participants had to estimate whether there were more black or white squares in the figure (in reality, all figures contained 90 black and 90 white squares; De Gilder & Wilke, 1994). After participants had answered, the next figure appeared on the computer screen. Participants completed eight such tasks. After completion of the tasks, participants were informed that their performance did not deviate much from the performance of most participants. Participants were then asked how much fun and how boring (reverse scored) the tasks were (1 � not at all, 7 � very much). These two items were averaged into a reliable task evalu- ation scale (� � .71). Following the tasks, the procedure manipulation was adminis- tered. This manipulation was the same as in Study 1. Participants then responded to the questions that pertained to the dependent variables and manipulation checks. To measure perceived proce- dural justice, the measure of Experiment 1 was extended with two additional questions. The resulting five-item scale consisted of the following questions: “How fair was the way you were treated by the experimenter?” (1 � very unfair, 7 � very fair), “How just was the way you were treated by the experimenter?” (1 � very unjust, 7 � very just), “How appropriate was the way you were treated by the experimenter? (1 � very inappropriate, 7 � very appropriate), “How correct were you treated by the experimenter?” (1 � not correct, 7 � very correct), and “How respectful were you treated by the experimenter? (1 � not respectful, 7 � very respectful). These five items were averaged into a reliable procedural justice scale (� � .91). The manipulation checks were assessed after the measurement of procedural justice. To check the autonomy manipulation, the following three questions were posed (1 � not at all, 7 � very much): “To what extent did you feel free to decide for yourself what task you wanted to do?” “To what extent could you choose yourself what task you wanted to do?” and “To what extent did you have the feeling that you could influence what task you would do?” These three items were averaged into a reliable autonomy manipulation check scale (� � .92). To check the procedure manipulation, the same two questions as in Study 1 were posed. Again, these two items were averaged into a reliable procedure manipulation check scale (� � .86). After this, the experiment ended, and participants were fully debriefed, thanked, and paid for their participation. Results Manipulation checks. The manipulations were checked with 3 � 2 ANOVAs. The analysis on the autonomy manipulation check scale revealed only a significant autonomy main effect, F(2, 102) � 118.67, p � .001. According to Tukey’s honestly signif- icant difference (HSD) tests, all three conditions differed signifi- cantly from one another (all ps � .001). Participants in the choice condition experienced more autonomy (M � 6.25, SD � 0.76) than participants in the no-choice condition (M � 1.96, SD � 1.15). Participants in the control condition reported less experi- enced autonomy than participants in the choice condition, but more experienced autonomy than participants in the no-choice condition (M � 3.50, SD � 1.53). As was intended, explicitly being denied choice (as was the case in the no-choice condition) caused a stronger decrease in experienced autonomy than not being made aware of choice possibilities (as was the case in the control condition). Analysis of the procedure manipulation check scale revealed only a procedure main effect, F(1, 102) � 299.11, p � .001. Participants in the voice condition perceived more opportunities for voicing their opinion (M � 5.32, SD � 1.36) than did partic- ipants in the no-voice condition (M � 1.51, SD � 0.92). These results indicated that participants perceived the two experimental manipulations as intended. Furthermore, the fact that only the intended main effects were observed for the manipulation checks suggest that the attempt to orthogonally induce the autonomy and procedure manipulations was successful. Choices for tasks. In the choice condition, 15 participants chose the contrast sensitivity task, and 22 participants chose the intuitive decision task. This distribution does not deviate signifi- cantly from the expected 50% distribution, 2(1, N � 15) � 1.32, p � .25. This analysis ensured that participants did not structurally prefer one of the choice options. Task evaluation. A 3 � 2 ANOVA performed on the task evaluation scale yielded no significant effects. Of particular im- 2 The descriptions of the “contrast sensitivity task” and the “intuitive decision task” were brief and ambiguous. This ensured that the contingen- cies of the actual task were in correspondence with both options, enabling all participants in the choice condition to recognize their choice in the nature of the task. 1171AUTONOMY AND PROCEDURAL JUSTICE portance was the fact that the autonomy main effect was nonsig- nificant, F(2, 102) � 1.11, p � .33. Participants in the various experimental conditions evaluated the task as equally positive or negative. Experienced valence of the task can thus not explain the results reported here. Procedural justice. The means and standard deviations are displayed in Table 1. As a first analysis, I conducted a 3 � 2 ANOVA on perceived procedural justice. This analysis revealed a significant procedure main effect, F(1, 102) � 9.41, p � .01, indicating that participants in the voice condition reported higher levels of perceived procedural justice (M � 4.69, SD � 1.29) than participants in the no-voice condition (M � 3.93, SD � 1.42). The main effect of autonomy was nonsignificant, F(2, 102) � 1.58, p � .21. More important was that this analysis indicated a signif- icant interaction, F(2, 102) � 3.90, p � .03. I then proceeded to more directly test the hypothesis by means of interaction contrast analyses. The most straightforward test of the hypothesis was the comparison of the procedure effect in the choice condition versus the procedure effect in the no-choice condition. This analysis indicated a significant interaction contrast, F(1, 102) � 7.63, p � .01. In correspondence with the hypothesis, the procedure simple main effect was significant in the no-choice condition, F(1, 102) � 13.27, p � .001, but was nonsignificant in the choice condition (F � 1). That is, people respond more strongly to voice versus no-voice procedures when they previously had been denied choice in an unrelated domain than when they had been provided with choice in an unrelated domain. Two other relevant interaction contrasts are the comparison of the procedure effect in the control condition with the procedure effect in (a) the choice condition and (b) the no-choice condition. The first interaction contrast is informative about whether provid- ing choice reduced the relative strength of the procedure manipu- lation, and the second interaction contrast is informative about whether denying choice magnified the relative strength of the procedure manipulation. The first interaction contrast was nonsig- nificant, F(1, 102) � 2.22, p � .13, as was the second interaction contrast, F(1, 102) � 1.73, p � .19. These analyses indicated that the procedure effect in the control condition was intermediate between the procedure effects in the choice and no-choice condi- tions. Thus, the results suggest that both providing and not providing choice contributed to the differential impact of the procedure manipulation in the autonomy conditions. To investigate this pos- sibility further, I examined the effects of autonomy in both pro- cedure conditions. When observing the means displayed in Table 1, it appears that in the no-choice condition, participants displayed an increase in the value that they assigned to voice opportunities when compared with the choice and control conditions. A contrast analysis among participants in the voice condition that pitted the no-choice condition against the choice and control conditions indeed was significant, F(1, 102) � 5.08, p � .03. Furthermore, the pattern of means suggests that in the choice condition, partic- ipants may have responded less negatively to a no-voice procedure as compared with the other two conditions. Indeed, a contrast analysis within the no-voice condition that pitted the choice con- dition against the no-choice and control conditions was significant, F(1, 102) � 5.29, p � .03. These analyses suggest that being denied choice causes people to respond more positively to voice procedures and that being provided with choice decreases the negative impact of no-voice procedures. Discussion The results provided further support for the general hypothesis that the extent to which people’s autonomy needs are thwarted versus satisfied predicts their sensitivity to variations in procedural justice, as procedural justice judgments were influenced more strongly by the procedure manipulation when choice was denied than when choice was provided. Furthermore, inclusion of the control condition suggested that both deprivation and satisfaction of autonomy may be associated with procedural justice: The rel- ative difference between the choice and no-choice conditions was attributable to both a relative decrease in sensitivity to procedural justice when choice had been provided and to a relative increase in sensitivity to procedural justice when choice had not been pro- vided. When deprived of autonomy (i.e., choice has not been provided), results suggested that people increasingly value proce- dural justice cues that are supportive of their autonomy (i.e., voice procedures). When autonomy has been supported (i.e., choice has been provided), results suggested that people become relatively less sensitive to procedural justice cues that could potentially threaten their autonomy (i.e., no-voice procedures). These latter findings are in correspondence with Study 1, in which both the voice and no-voice conditions contributed to the interactive effect of autonomy and procedure on procedural justice judgments. Taken together, the results obtained in Studies 1 and 2 are consis- tent with the theoretical notion that people attend to the fairness of Table 1 Means and Standard Deviations of Participants’ Procedural Justice Judgments As a Function of Autonomy and Procedure in Study 2 Procedure Autonomy Choice Control No choice M SD M SD M SD Voice 4.41b,c 1.44 4.40b,c 1.19 5.31a 1.05 No voice 4.51a,c 1.52 3.60b 1.4 3.68b,c 1.19 Note. Higher means indicate more positive procedural justice judgments. Means with no subscript in common differ significantly at p � .05. 1172 VAN PROOIJEN decision-making procedures to regulate their basic autonomy needs. Manipulating both choice and voice in the same experiment may raise questions about the orthogonality of the experimental manip- ulations. In the present experiment, however, I found empirical indications that the two manipulations were induced indepen- dently. First, the manipulation checks revealed that the autonomy manipulation did not influence the extent to which participants perceived voice opportunities, and the procedure manipulation did not influence the autonomy manipulation check. Thus, both ma- nipulations only exerted the intended main effects on the manip- ulation checks, which suggests that the manipulations were per- ceived as independent by the participants. Second, whereas the procedure manipulation exerted a main effect on procedural justice judgments, which is in correspondence with previous research (Folger, 1977; cf. Brockner et al., 1998; Lind et al., 1990; Tyler, 1987; Van den Bos, 2003; Van Prooijen et al., 2004), the auton- omy manipulation did not exert such a main effect on procedural justice judgments. These findings suggest that the two manipula- tions had different psychological implications for participants. In particular, the results were in correspondence with the theoretical notion that manipulating choice directly satisfies versus deprives autonomy needs (Deci & Ryan, 1985) but that procedural justice may serve as a heuristic cue that informs recipients about the extent to which a decision maker has the intention to behave in ways that are supportive of autonomy needs. Study 3 Study 3 was designed to extend Studies 1 and 2 in three meaningful ways. First, the results of Studies 1 and 2 are limited to the effects of voice versus no-voice procedures. Although these variations in decision-making procedures have a strong and robust influence on justice-based responses and are central to the proce- dural justice literature, there are more criteria that determine whether people judge procedures to be fair versus unfair (Lev- enthal, 1980). In addition, voice procedures give recipients a sense of agency, and hence, one might argue that voice procedures are more directly associated with autonomy needs than other proce- dural justice criteria. In Study 3, I focused on general perceptions of procedural justice instead of specific manipulations of voice versus no-voice procedures. In particular, participants completed a procedural justice scale that was validated by Colquitt (2001), which is designed to assess all of Leventhal’s (1980) procedural justice criteria. As such, I examined in Study 3 whether the key hypothesis is corroborated using a broader operational definition of procedural justice. Second, the results of Studies 1 and 2 are limited to the psy- chological laboratory and to the specific population of university students. Although laboratory experiments are well suited to in- vestigate the causal influence of theoretical constructs on depen- dent variables while assuring high internal validity, one may question whether the processes observed in the laboratory gener- alize to situations outside of the laboratory and to different popu- lations. To evaluate the generalizability of the present findings, I investigated whether further evidence for the present conclusions would be observed outside of the psychological laboratory. There- fore, I tested the present hypothesis among public employees of the government of a large Dutch city, who reported on the extent to which they considered their work to be supportive of autonomy. Study 3 thus extended the previous studies by focusing on public employees rather than on university students and by assessing a real-life indicator of participants’ autonomy. As a third extension, Study 3 focused on the applied implica- tions of the present ideas for organizations. These implications were investigated by examining whether perceived procedural justice would interact with experienced work autonomy to influ- ence various perceptions and behaviors that are important for healthy organizational functioning. Such pro-organizational re- sponses have been associated with both procedural justice (Tyler & Lind, 1992) as well as with organizational implications of self-determination theory (Gagné & Deci, 2005). As pro- organizational perceptions, I measured participants’ identification with the organization (Huo, Smith, Tyler, & Lind, 1996) and the extent to which they feel respected by their organization (De Cremer & Tyler, 2005; Sleebos, Ellemers, & De Gilder, 2006). Whereas identification refers to the extent to which people psy- chologically connect themselves to the group, respect refers to the extent people believe that the group values and appreciates them. Previous research indeed indicates that identification and respect are empirically related, yet conceptually distinct constructs (e.g., Simon & Stürmer, 2003). As an indicator of pro-organizational behavior, I assessed the extent to which participants are inclined to report illegal or im- moral actions of their colleagues to their superiors. Such “whistle blowing” is an important variable in research on organizational ethics because it facilitates the cessation of wrongdoing in orga- nizations, which may benefit employees, stockholders, and society in general (Micelli, Near, & Schwenk, 1991). Although whistle blowing intentions have been argued to be associated with proce- dural justice (Near, Dworkin, & Micelli, 1993), the influence of procedural justice on this morality-based behavior is as yet not well documented by empirical social-psychological research. By including whistle blowing intentions as a dependent measure, the present study sought to (a) provide further evidence that proce- dural justice phenomena hold implications for this important morality-based behavior, and, more important for the present pur- poses, (b) test whether the relation between autonomy and proce- dural justice may generalize to pro-organizational behaviors. It is expected that the specified pro-organizational perceptions and behaviors are influenced more strongly by variations in procedural justice among public employees who experience low as opposed to high autonomy in their work. Method Participant sample. The study was conducted among public employees of the government of one of the largest cities in the Netherlands. Out of 161 public employees who were initially contacted by means of a telephone call, 113 public employees eventually completed and returned the questionnaire (a response rate of 70.2%). The final sample included 73 men, 35 women, and 5 participants who did not indicate their gender (mean age � 41.99 years, SD � 9.66). Procedure. Public employees were first approached by means of a telephone call to ask whether they were willing to participate in the study. Public employees who agreed to participate would receive the questionnaire and a return envelope in the mail. Par- 1173AUTONOMY AND PROCEDURAL JUSTICE ticipants could either send in the questionnaire by means of the return envelope or hand in the questionnaire to a research assistant who visited their department at an announced date. Participation was on a voluntary basis, and participants’ answers to the ques- tions were treated as anonymous and confidential. Questionnaire. The measures were part of a larger question- naire that also served applied purposes. To measure perceived procedural justice, the seven items developed by Colquitt (2001) to assess procedural justice were administered to the participants. This scale is based on the procedural justice rules proposed by Leventhal (1980). The questions started with “Whenever decisions are taken at my department. . . . ”, followed by, for example “. . . I am able to express my thoughts and feelings” “. . . . the employed procedures are applied consistently” and “. . . the decisions are based on accurate information” (1 � strongly disagree, 7 � strongly agree). The seven items were averaged into a reliable procedural justice scale (� � .74).3 To measure the extent to which participants experienced a sense of autonomy in their work, they indicated to what extent their employment supported choice on a variety of dimensions. These dimensions included freedom in how to organize the various task demands, how to apply the skills one has acquired, and how to evaluate results. In particular, participants were asked to what extent their work contained the following characteristics (1 � not at all, 7 � very much): “Freedom to choose your own work methods” “Responsibility” “The opportunity to evaluate the qual- ity of your work yourself” “Variation in the tasks” and “The opportunity to use your capabilities.” These five items were aver- aged into a reliable autonomy scale (� � .79). Organizational identification was measured with three items (1 � strongly disagree, 7 � strongly agree): “At this moment, I identify with my department” “At this moment, I want to do my best for my department” and “At this moment, I feel connected to my department.” These measures were averaged into a reliable measure of organizational identification (� � .72). Perceived respect from the organization was measured with three items (1 � strongly disagree, 7 � strongly agree): “The department appreciates my contribution” “The department shows consideration for my goals and values” and “The department genuinely cares about my well-being.” These three items were averaged into a reliable respect scale (� � .81). To measure whistle blowing, participants were presented with six brief hypothetical scenarios regarding integrity violations com- mitted by a public employee. To ensure realism, all scenarios were based on incidents that in previous years had actually been re- ported at the city government’s Department of Integrity.4 An example of an integrity violation scenario is the following: Coincidently, a relative of the public employee who works at a service desk applies for a license. According to the rules, the relative is legally entitled to this license. But because the public employee privately is at odds with this particular relative, he refuses to grant the license. The other scenarios described sharing of classified information with unauthorized individuals, searching the government’s com- puter files for information concerning the financial situation of one’s ex-wife in order to gain advantage in a custody battle, smoking marijuana while on duty (and while driving a company car), a male public employee sexually harassing a female public employee, and a public employee who was bribed to falsify sig- natures on a wedding document. After each scenario, participants indicated their agreement to the following statement: “I would report this incident to this public employee’s direct supervisor” (1 � strongly disagree, 7 � strongly agree). Consequently, six items measured the extent to which participants were inclined to “blow the whistle” in response to six diverse integrity violations. These six items were averaged into a reliable whistle blowing scale (� � .89). Results Exploratory factor analysis. To investigate whether the mea- surement of autonomy was distinct from the measurement of procedural justice, I first conducted an exploratory factor analysis (principal-axis factoring) on the items that formed the autonomy and procedural justice scales. Given that measures of respect conceptually are closely related to procedural justice (De Cremer & Tyler, 2005), I also included the respect items in this analysis. A three-factor solution with oblimin rotation was imposed a priori according to the theoretical expectation that autonomy, procedural justice, and respect are empirically distinct constructs. These three factors (Eigenvalues � 1.60) had pattern coefficients that sup- ported the notion that autonomy, procedural justice, and respect are empirically distinct. The five autonomy items all had high pattern coefficients (|fij| � .40) on the first factor but not on the second or third factor. This provides empirical evidence that the five autonomy items indeed all reflect the same underlying psy- chological construct. The three respect items had high pattern coefficients on the second factor but not on the first or third factor; and, out of seven procedural justice items, six had high pattern coefficients on the third but not on the first or second factor. The only deviating item in the procedural justice scale was the item whether the employed procedures are applied consistently; this item did not load well on any factor. To keep Colquitt’s (2001) original procedural justice measure intact, I retained this item in the analyses below (results were similar when this item was excluded). Hierarchical regression analyses. Table 2 displays the means, standard deviations, and intercorrelations for the variables that were assessed in Study 3. In correspondence with Study 1, the hypothesis was tested by means of hierarchical regression analy- ses. Both the autonomy and procedural justice scales were cen- tered, and the interaction term was based on the product of these centered variables (Cohen et al., 2003). Step 1 tested for main effects, and the interaction was added to the regression model in Step 2. The results of the hierarchical regression analyses are displayed in Table 3. Step 1 was nonsignificant for whistle blowing (R2 � .04), F(2, 110) � 2.06, p � .13, but Step 1 was significant for both identification (R2 � .21), F(2, 110) � 14.76, p � .001, and for 3 One of the items in the procedural justice scale referred to voice opportunities, and another item referred to process control. It is noteworthy that when these two items (which are arguably most closely associated with autonomy concerns) were dropped from the scale, the analyses still re- vealed the predicted interactions on the dependent variables. 4 I thank the Department of Integrity for granting my research assistants access to their files. No public employees of the Department of Integrity were included in the sample. 1174 VAN PROOIJEN respect (R2 � .20), F(2, 110) � 13.50, p � .001. As can be seen in Table 3, the main effect of perceived procedural justice was a significant predictor of perceived respect from the organization, but not of organizational identification. The main effect of auton- omy significantly predicted both identification and perceived re- spect. More important for the present purposes, the Step 2 inter- action term was significant for all three dependent variables: for identification (�R2 � .04), F(1, 109) � 5.23, p � .03; for respect (�R2 � .04), F(1, 109) � 5.09, p � .03; and for whistle blowing (�R2 � .04), F(1, 109) � 4.97, p � .03. The interactions on the three dependent variables are displayed graphically in Figure 2. To examine the nature of these interac- tions, I conducted simple slopes analyses for all dependent vari- ables. Among participants who scored low in autonomy, proce- dural justice was a strong and significant predictor of identification (� � .48, p � .001), perceived respect (� � .60, p � .001), and whistle blowing (� � .42, p � .01). Among participants who scored high in autonomy, procedural justice was not a significant predictor of identification (� � �.11, p � .41), perceived respect (� � .13, p � .32), or whistle blowing (� � .03, p � .80). Taken together, these results supported the hypothesis for all dependent variables, replicating and extending the laboratory findings of Studies 1 and 2 in a field setting. Finally, I tested whether the effects of autonomy were most pronounced following experiences of procedural justice or injus- tice. Autonomy was not a significant predictor of any of the dependent variables among participants who scored high on the procedural justice scale (all ps � .22). Among participants who scored low on the procedural justice scale, however, autonomy significantly predicted identification (� � .55, p � .001), respect (� � .51, p � .001), but not whistle blowing (� � .20, p � .19). These different patterns for the dependent variables may be ex- plained by assuming that whistle blowing behaviors are associated with more complex psychological dynamics than perceptual re- sponses, given that whistle blowing behaviors can be costly in terms of potential retaliation (Near et al., 1993). In addition, it can be noted that effects of autonomy on identification and respect are most pronounced in response to procedural injustice, which is inconsistent with the results of Studies 1 and 2. I return to this finding below. Discussion Study 3 replicated and extended the findings of Studies 1 and 2. Results supported the central hypothesis with a broader operation- alization of procedural justice, and in a population of public employees. Furthermore, Study 3 suggested that the interactive effects of procedural justice with autonomy can have substantial implications for organizations. This was evidenced by the fact that the predicted interaction was observed for both pro-organizational perceptions (i.e., identification and respect) and behaviors (i.e., whistle blowing). These pro-organizational perceptions and behav- iors are important for healthy organizational functioning (De Cre- mer & Tyler, 2005; Huo et al., 1996; Micelli et al., 1991; Near et al., 1993; Sleebos et al., 2006). As such, Study 3 strengthens confidence in both the validity and the applicability of the theo- retical proposition that people attend to variations in procedural justice to regulate their basic autonomy needs. Whereas in Studies 1 and 2 the influence of autonomy on procedural justice judgments did not clearly differ for voice versus no-voice procedures, in Study 3 the influence of autonomy on identification and respect was most pronounced in response to procedural injustice. This differential finding is most likely caused by subtle differences between experimentally inducing a voice or no-voice procedure versus measuring procedural justice using Colquitt’s (2001) procedural justice scale. As noted earlier, voice Table 2 Means, Standard Deviations, and Intercorrelations of the Measures Assessed in Study 3 Measure M SD 1 2 3 4 5 1. Procedural justice 4.51 0.96 — 2. Autonomy 5.48 0.98 .46��� — 3. Organizational identification 5.23 1.26 .27�� .46��� — 4. Perceived respect 4.37 1.28 .40��� .36��� .52��� — 5. Whistle blowing 5.01 1.61 .19� .11 .26�� .15 — �p � .05. �� p � .01. ��� p � .001. Table 3 Results From Hierarchical Regression Analyses in Study 3 Variable Identification Perceived respect Whistle blowing � t(110) � t(110) � t(110) Step 1 Procedural justice .08 0.82 .30 3.09�� .17 1.64 Autonomy .42 4.40��� .22 2.29� .03 0.31 Step 2 t(109) t(109) t(109) Procedural Justice � Autonomy �.20 �2.29� �.20 �2.26� �.22 �2.23� �p � .05. �� p � .01. ��� p � .001. 1175AUTONOMY AND PROCEDURAL JUSTICE procedures may be more closely associated with autonomy than other procedural justice criteria, in that opportunities to voice one’s opinion create a sense of agency and active participation. As such, voice procedures may be of particular relevance in buffering oneself against deprivations of autonomy. These specific features of voice procedures are less relevant when measuring a broader range of procedural justice criteria (Leventhal, 1980). Across var- ious procedural justice criteria, people may be particularly sensi- tive to unfair procedures as a function of the extent to which autonomy needs are thwarted. This possibility is consistent with previous arguments that the negative impact of injustice on per- ception and behavior is stronger than is the positive impact of justice (Folger, 1984; Folger & Cropanzano, 1998; Van den Bos & Van Prooijen, 2001; Van Prooijen, De Cremer, et al., 2008; Van Prooijen, Van den Bos, Lind, & Wilke, 2006; cf. Baumeister, Bratlavsky, Finkenauer, & Vohs, 2001). Be that as it may, such differential impact of fair versus unfair procedures does not com- promise the main conclusion of the present contribution, which is that people are more sensitive to variations in procedural justice when they experience low as opposed to high autonomy in various domains. General Discussion The three studies reported herein provided consistent evidence for the proposition that deprivation versus gratification of auton- omy needs predicts people’s fairness-based responses to decision- making procedures. The general hypothesis was supported when autonomy was measured as an individual-difference variable (Study 1), when autonomy was experimentally manipulated (Study 2), and when autonomy was measured as a property of people’s employment (Study 3). Furthermore, the results of the studies converged as a product of manipulations of voice versus no-voice procedures (Studies 1 and 2) as well as assessments of global procedural justice in organizations (Study 3). The findings were replicated both in the laboratory and in a field setting, and the predicted interaction was evident for both procedural justice judg- ments and for various pro-organizational perceptions (identifica- tion and respect) and behaviors (whistle blowing). Taken together, the findings of the three studies support the propositions that the extent to which autonomy needs are satisfied hold implications for people’s fairness-based responses to decision-making procedures and that a complete answer to the question of why procedural justice matters to people must take human autonomy needs into account. In particular, the results presented here are in strong agreement with the underlying theoretical claim that people attend to the fairness of decision-making procedures as a means of regulating their basic autonomy needs. The present findings have theoretical implications for the inte- gration of self-determination theory (Deci & Ryan, 1985, 2000) and procedural justice theories (Lind et al., 1993; Tyler & Blader, 2003; Tyler & Lind, 1992; Van den Bos & Lind, 2002; Van den Bos et al., 1998). According to self-determination theory, people seek fulfillment of three basic psychological needs—autonomy, relatedness, and competence. The present research focused on autonomy needs by revealing that people’s fairness-based re- sponses are more sensitive to the way they are treated by authority figures when they are deprived of autonomy. In light of other findings in the procedural justice literature, it is noteworthy that relatedness and competence needs also are substantially related to procedural justice. For instance, researchers have found that pro- cedural justice is functional to regulate one’s sense of relatedness, in that fair versus unfair procedures are informative about the extent to which one is included in or excluded from social groups (e.g., De Cremer, 2002; Smith, Tyler, Huo, Ortiz, & Lind, 1998; Tyler, 1994; Van Prooijen, Gallucci, & Toeset, 2008; Van Prooijen et al., 2004). Likewise, empirical research has linked a concern for procedural justice with indicators of one’s competence, such as performance-based status (Diekmann, Sondak, & Barsness, 2007; Tyler & Blader, 2002; Van Prooijen et al., 2002, 2005). These previous findings, in conjunction with the findings of the present research, suggest that one of the main reasons why people might care about the fairness of decision-making procedures is because these procedures are functional to inform people about the extent to which the social environment supports versus undermines basic psychological needs. Hence, procedural justice may be more closely associated with social motives and needs than has been recognized before. Further empirical examination may inform DV: Identification 4 5 6 Low autonomy High autonomy High PJ Low PJ DV: Respect 3 4 5 6 Low autonomy High autonomy High PJ Low PJ DV: Whistle blowing 4 5 6 Low autonomy High autonomy High PJ Low PJ Figure 2. The three dependent variables (DVs) as a function of autonomy and procedural justice (PJ) in Study 3. 1176 VAN PROOIJEN scientists about the more general question of why people care about the fairness of decision-making procedures, and may inte- grate procedural justice theories with self-determination theory (Deci & Ryan, 1985) and with related theoretical perspectives on social motives and needs (e.g., Fiske, 2004). The fact that the key hypothesis was tested by means of various research methods (i.e., laboratory experiments and a field study; various operationalizations of independent variables) has at least two noteworthy advantages. First, this variation in research pro- cedures ensures that the present findings are not an artifact of one or the other method, but rather that the present findings reflect a genuine and impactful phenomenon that can be observed in vari- ous ways and in a variety of social situations. As such, the observed support for the hypothesis is indicative for the robustness of the present findings. Second, the limitations of one study are complemented by the strengths of other studies. For instance, one might argue that the laboratory setting of Studies 1 and 2 is artificial, raising questions about the extent to which the relation between procedural justice and autonomy has any meaning in everyday life situations. This limitation, however, was addressed in Study 3, which revealed that the present ideas can have far- reaching consequences in a real-life organizational setting. In a similar vein, one might argue that Study 3 rests on correlational findings and is thus subject to questions about causality and alternative explanations (e.g., constructs that may be correlated with the autonomy measure). For instance, public employees with more autonomy may also have more power, or be higher in the organizational hierarchy. These limitations were addressed in Study 2, in which autonomy and procedure were orthogonally manipulated to reveal a causal influence on procedural justice judgments. Furthermore, it seems unlikely that the measure of trait autonomy in Study 1 reflects differences in power or status. As such, the variety of methods that were used here helps to rule out alternative explanations and increases confidence in the validity and applicability of the present conclusions. Although the present article proposed that autonomy and pro- cedural justice are closely related, it is important to note that a procedural justice manipulation cannot be equated with an auton- omy manipulation. Being allowed voice does not automatically imply choice, as authorities do not have to listen to the concerns of subordinates (Lind et al., 1990). Indeed, in a complex social environment where opinions differ substantially among various subordinates, or where painful decisions are necessary for the collective interest, it may be unavoidable for decision makers to disregard the opinions of some or all of the subordinates. Subor- dinates often are well aware of this, and, as such, it is plausible that subordinates interpret voice opportunities, or other indications that procedures were fair (Leventhal, 1980), as evidence that decision makers are at least willing to make an effort to be supportive of autonomy. Thus, whereas choice opportunities directly address autonomy needs (Deci & Ryan, 1985, 2000; Moller et al., 2006), opportunities to voice an opinion are more likely to be regarded as an indirect heuristic cue to estimate the extent to which a decision maker has the intention to behave in ways that are supportive of autonomy (Lind et al., 1993; Van den Bos et al., 1998). Empiri- cally, the results indeed suggested that autonomy and procedural justice were independent in the present studies. For instance, in Study 2, manipulation checks indicated that the choice and voice manipulations were induced independently. Furthermore, the fac- tor analysis in Study 3 revealed that the items measuring autonomy loaded on a different factor than the items measuring procedural justice. In future research, it would be interesting to find out to what extent procedural justice manipulations are effective in re- storing autonomy deficiencies. Establishing such a relation would further refine the model of procedural justice as an autonomy- regulating tool that was presented in the present contribution. The theoretical rationale that underlies the present work was partly based on social-cognitive procedural justice theories, spe- cifically, fairness heuristic theory (Lind et al., 1993; Van den Bos et al., 1998) and the related uncertainty management model (Van den Bos & Lind, 2002). These theories assign a major role to human uncertainty to explain procedural justice effects, as indi- cated by findings that feelings of uncertainty increases people’s sensitivity to procedural justice manipulations (Van den Bos, 2001; see also De Cremer & Sedikides, 2005). Although these insights contributed to the line of reasoning underlying the present hypothesis, it is important to note that measurements or manipu- lations of autonomy are not likely to simultaneously measure or manipulate uncertainty. For instance, many empirical studies re- vealed that low-trait or situational autonomy is associated with numerous detrimental life outcomes (Deci et al., 1999; Deci & Ryan, 2000, 2002; Sheldon et al., 2004), but to the best of my knowledge, no evidence has yet documented that these detrimental effects are mediated by feelings of uncertainty. Also, it does not seem plausible to assume that the effects of the autonomy manip- ulation in Study 2 are attributable to feelings of uncertainty. That is, feelings of uncertainty generally reflect a desire for meaning and structure in an unpredictable social environment (Van den Bos & Lind, 2002). This does not apply to the autonomy conditions of Study 2, as participants in all conditions knew for certain what task they would perform (in fact, all participants had completed the task before encountering the manipulation of voice versus no-voice procedure). Taken together, it does not seem likely that the present findings can alternatively be explained by the assertion that low autonomy increases feelings of uncertainty. Indeed, if there were a relation between uncertainty and choice, it would be plausible to argue that excessive choice is associated with increased uncertainty— high choice increases unpredictability in light of unclarity about what choice option would best serve one’s goals. As such, in Study 2, I took care to limit individuals’ choice options to only two possibilities. Such limitation in the number of choice options is in correspondence with previous research in which positive consequences of choice were studied (Moller et al., 2006; Zuckerman et al., 1978). In this regard, it is noteworthy that empirical research suggests that there indeed are limits to the amount of choice that people consider to be desirable, as people can experience “choice overload” when confronted with too many options. Such choice overload has been found to be demotivating in a variety of situations (Iyengar & Lepper, 2000). These ideas point to interesting avenues for future research de- signed to further disentangle the relation between choice and procedural justice. For instance, whereas the present research revealed that a modest number of choice opportunities decreases people’s responsiveness to procedural justice, one might speculate that an excessive number of choice opportunities would increase people’s responsiveness to procedural justice. Justice has been argued to provide structure and meaning to social situations (Van den Bos & Lind, 2002), and hence people may feel a particular 1177AUTONOMY AND PROCEDURAL JUSTICE need for justice when they face a situation that is unpredictable given the necessity to choose between an excessive number of options. The present research may also have theoretical and practical implications for the question of which leaders are effective in coordinating a group toward a collective goal (Van Vugt et al., 2008). Self-determination theory predicts that leaders who are supportive of autonomy will intrinsically motivate followers, thereby increasing team performance (Deci et al., 1999; Gagné & Deci, 2005). This is consistent with research indicating that the unnecessary exercise of control by an external leader can lead to dissatisfaction among members of a self-managing team (Morge- son, 2005). The insights presented here identified a tool that is functional for leaders to behave in an autonomy-supportive way. By implementing fair decision-making procedures—for instance, by listening to the concerns of subordinates, by being transparent, and by exerting efforts to be an unbiased and consistent decision maker—leaders may be able to elicit pro-organizational responses particularly from followers who do not feel very autonomous in their work or other life domains. This insight may be useful to corporate managers, given that pro-organizational responses, such as those investigated in Study 3 of the present contribution, are associated with healthy organizational functioning (cf. De Cremer & Tyler, 2005; Huo et al., 1996; Near et al., 1993). Furthermore, future research may investigate the extent to which the present findings generalize to other social situations and mea- sures, to more tightly integrate the autonomy and procedural justice domains. In separate lines of research, autonomy and pro- cedural justice both have been shown to shape a variety of human responses in educational settings, health care situations, sports teams, friendships and intimate relationships, and numerous other important life domains (Deci & Ryan, 2000, 2002; Lind & Tyler, 1988; Tyler & Lind, 1992). Informed by the present findings, it seems likely that human perception and behavior in many different situations are influenced by the interplay between autonomy and justice concerns. Furthermore, procedural justice research may start incorporating dependent variables that are typically associ- ated with the self-determination of behavior, such as persistence in goal pursuit, psychological adjustment, and intrinsic motivation. Future research would do well to scrutinize these relations in a wide range of social settings. To conclude, the present research was initiated to establish an empirical relation between the fundamental human need for au- tonomy and people’s concern for procedural justice. The findings indeed suggest such a relation, supporting a model that predicts procedural justice to be functional for the regulation of autonomy needs. As such, the present research may be informative about broader questions surrounding human morality. For instance, one might speculate that the deprivation of basic psychological needs places people in a psychological state that causes them to evaluate behavior from a moral point of view. That is, deprivation of basic psychological needs (autonomy, belongingness) may be associated in fundamental ways with people’s concern for morality, as people may desire a fair decision-making structure that is likely to support these basic psychological needs. The present findings increase the empirical basis for such a fundamental relation between need fulfillment and human morality. It can be concluded that the need for autonomy is important to understand why the quality of decision-making procedures exerts such strong and pervasive ef- fects on fairness judgments and related perceptions and behaviors. References Baumeister, R. F., Bratlavsky, E., Finkenauer, C., & Vohs, K. D. (2001). Bad is stronger than good. Review of General Psychology, 5, 323–370. Baumeister, R. F., & Leary, M. R. (1995). The need to belong: Desire for interpersonal attachments as a fundamental human motive. Psychologi- cal Bulletin, 117, 497–529. Bies, R. J., & Moag, J. S. (1986). Interactional justice. In R. J. Lewicki, B. M. Sheppard, & M. H. Bazerman (Eds.), Research on negotiations in organizations (Vol. 1, pp. 43–55). Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. Boehm, C. (1999). Hierarchy in the forest: The evolution of egalitarian behavior. London: Harvard University Press. Brehm, S. S., & Brehm, J. W. (1981). Psychological reactance: A theory of freedom and control. New York: Academic Press. Brockner, J., Heuer, L., Siegel, P. A., Wiesenfeld, B., Martin, C., Grover, S., et al. (1998). The moderating effect of self-esteem in reaction to voice: Converging evidence from five studies. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 75, 394 – 407. Brockner, J., & Wiesenfeld, B. M. (1996). An integrative framework for explaining reactions to decisions: Interactive effects of outcomes and procedures. Psychological Bulletin, 120, 189 –208. Cohen, J., Cohen, P., West, S. G., & Aiken, L. S. (2003). Applied multiple regression/correlation analysis for the behavioral sciences (3rd ed.). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Colquitt, J. A. (2001). On the dimensionality of organizational justice: A construct validation of a measure. Journal of Applied Psychology, 86, 386 – 400. Cranston, M. (1968). The social contract. Harmondsworth, England: Pen- guin Books. (Original work published 1762). Cropanzano, R., Byrne, Z. S., Bobocel, D. R., & Rupp, D. E. (2001). Moral virtues, fairness heuristics, social entities, and other denizens of organi- zational justice. Journal of Vocational Behavior, 58, 164 –209. Deci, E. L., Koestner, R., & Ryan, R. M. (1999). A meta-analytic review of experiments examining the effects of extrinsic rewards on intrinsic motivation. Psychological Bulletin, 125, 627– 668. Deci, E. L., & Ryan, R. M. (1985). Intrinsic motivation and self- determination in human behavior. New York: Plenum Press. Deci, E. L., & Ryan, R. M. (2000). The “what” and “why” of goal pursuits: Human needs and the self-determination of behavior. Psychological Inquiry, 11, 227–268. Deci, E. L., & Ryan, R. M. (2002). Handbook of self-determination research. Rochester, NY: The University of Rochester Press. De Cremer, D. (2002). Respect and cooperation in social dilemmas: The importance of feeling included. Personality and Social Psychology Bul- letin, 28, 1335–1341. De Cremer, D., & Sedikides, C. (2005). Self-uncertainty and responsive- ness to procedural justice. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 41, 157–173. De Cremer, D., & Tyler, T. R. (2005). Managing group behavior: The interplay between fairness, self, and cooperation. In M. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (pp. 151–218). New York: Academic Press. De Gilder, D., & Wilke, H. A. M. (1994). Expectation states theory and the motivational determinants of social influence. In W. Stroebe & M. Hewstone (Eds.), European review of social psychology (Vol. 5, pp. 243–269). London: Wiley. Diekmann, K. A., Sondak, H., & Barsness, Z. I. (2007). Does fairness matter more to some than to others? The moderating role of workplace status on the relationship between procedural fairness perceptions and job satisfaction. Social Justice Research, 20, 161–180. Fiske, S. T. (2004). Social beings: A core motives approach to social psychology. New York: Wiley. 1178 VAN PROOIJEN Folger, R. (1977). Distributive and procedural justice: Combined impact of “voice” and improvement on experienced inequity. Journal of Person- ality and Social Psychology, 35, 108 –119. Folger, R. (1984). Emerging issues in the social psychology of justice. In R. Folger (Ed.), The sense of injustice: Social psychological perspectives (pp. 3–24). New York: Plenum Press. Folger, R. (2001). Fairness as deonance. In S. W. Gilliland, D. D. Steiner, & D. P. Skarlicki (Eds.), Research in social issues in management (pp. 3–31). Information Age Publishers. Folger, R., & Cropanzano, R. (1998). Organizational justice and human resource management. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Folger, R., Rosenfield, D., Grove, J., & Corkran, L. (1979). Effects of “voice” and peer opinions on responses to inequity. Journal of Person- ality and Social Psychology, 37, 2253–2261. Gagné, M., & Deci, E. L. (2005). Self-determination theory and work motivation. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 26, 331–362. Houlden, P., LaTour, S., Walker, L., & Thibaut, J. (1978). Preference for modes of dispute resolution as a function of process and decision control. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 14, 13–30. Huo, Y. J., Smith, H. J., Tyler, T. R., & Lind, E. A. (1996). Superordinate identification, subgroup identification, and justice concerns: Is separat- ism the problem; is assimilation the answer? Psychological Science, 7, 40 – 45. Iyengar, S. S., & Lepper, M. R. (2000). When choice is demotivating: Can one desire too much of a good thing? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 79, 995–1006. Komorita, S. S., & Parks, C. D. (1994). Social dilemmas. Boulder, CO: Westview Press. Leventhal, G. S. (1980). What should be done with equity theory? New approaches to the study of fairness in social relationships. In K. J. Gergen, M. S. Greenberg, & R. H. Willis (Eds.), Social exchange: Advances on theory and research (pp. 27–54). New York: Plenum Press. Lind, E. A., Kanfer, R., & Earley, P. C. (1990). Voice, control, and procedural justice: Instrumental and noninstrumental concerns in fair- ness judgments. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 59, 952–959. Lind, E. A., Kulik, C. T., Ambrose, M., & De Vera-Park, M. V. (1993). Individual and corporate dispute resolution: Using procedural fairness as a decision heuristic. Administrative Science Quarterly, 38, 224 –251. Lind, E. A., & Tyler, T. R. (1988). The social psychology of procedural justice. New York: Plenum Press. Micelli, M. P., Near, J. P., & Schwenk, C. R. (1991). Who blows the whistle and why? Industrial & Labor Relations Review, 45, 113–129. Moller, A. C., Deci, E. L., & Ryan, R. M. (2006). Choice and ego- depletion: The moderating role of autonomy. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 32, 1024 –1036. Morgeson, F. P. (2005). The external leadership of self-managing teams: Intervening in the context of novel and disruptive events. Journal of Applied Psychology, 90, 497–508. Near, J. P., Dworkin, T. M., & Micelli, M. P. (1993). Explaining the whistle-blowing process: Suggestions from power theory and justice theory. Organization Science, 4, 393– 411. Paolucci, H. (1963). On crimes and punishment. Indianapolis, IN: Bobbs- Merrill. (Original work published 1764). Reis, H. T., Sheldon, K. M., Gable, S. L., Roscoe, J., & Ryan, R. M. (2000). Daily well-being: The role of autonomy, competence, and relat- edness. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 26, 419 – 435. Rozin, P., Lowery, L., Imada, S., & Haidt, J. (1999). The CAD triad hypothesis: A mapping between three moral emotions (contempt, anger, disgust) and three moral codes (community, autonomy, divinity). Jour- nal of Personality and Social Psychology, 76, 574 –586. Sheldon, K. M. (1995). Creativity and self-determination in personality. Creativity Research Journal, 8, 61–72. Sheldon, K. M., & Elliot, A. J. (1998). Not all personal goals are “per- sonal”: Comparing autonomous and controlling goals on effort and attainment. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 24, 546 –557. Sheldon, K. M., Ryan, R. M., Deci, E. L., & Kasser, T. (2004). The independent effects of goal contents and motives on well-being: It’s both what you pursue and why you pursue it. Personality and Social Psy- chology Bulletin, 30, 475– 486. Sheldon, K. M., Ryan, R. M., & Reis, H. (1996). What makes for a good day? Competence and autonomy in the day and in the person. Person- ality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 22, 1270 –1279. Simon, B., & Stürmer, S. (2003). Respect for group members: Intragroup determinants of collective identification and group-serving behavior. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 29, 183–193. Sleebos, E., Ellemers, N., & De Gilder, D. (2006). The carrot and the stick: Respected and disrespected group members’ motives to engage in group-serving efforts. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 32, 244 –255. Smith, H. J., Tyler, T. R., Huo, Y. J., Ortiz, D. J., & Lind, E. A. (1998). The self-relevant implications of the group-value model: Group membership, self-worth, and treatment quality. Journal of Experimental Social Psy- chology, 34, 470 – 493. Thibaut, J., & Walker, L. (1975). Procedural justice: A psychological analysis. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Tyler, T. R. (1987). Conditions leading to value expressive effects in judgments of procedural justice: A test of four models. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 52, 333–344. Tyler, T. R. (1994). Psychological models of the justice motive: Anteced- ents of distributive and procedural justice. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 5, 850 – 863. Tyler, T. R., & Blader, S. L. (2000). Cooperation in groups: Procedural justice, social identity, and behavioral engagement. Philadelphia: Psy- chology Press. Tyler, T. R., & Blader, S. L. (2002). Autonomous vs. comparative status: Must we be better than others to feel good about ourselves? Organiza- tional Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 89, 813– 838. Tyler, T. R., & Blader, S. L. (2003). The group engagement model: Procedural justice, social identity, and cooperative behavior. Personality and Social Psychology Review, 7, 349 –361. Tyler, T. R., & Lind, E. A. (1992). A relational model of authority in groups. In M. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 25, pp. 115–292). San Diego, CA: Academic Press. Van den Bos, K. (2001). Uncertainty management: The influence of human uncertainty on reactions to perceived fairness. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 80, 931–941. Van den Bos, K. (2003). On the subjective quality of social justice: The role of affect as information in the psychology of justice judgments. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 85, 482– 498. Van den Bos, K., & Lind, E. A. (2002). Uncertainty management by means of fairness judgments. In M. P. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 34, pp. 1– 60). San Diego, CA: Academic Press. Van den Bos, K., & Van Prooijen, J.-W. (2001). Referent cognitions theory: The psychology of voice depends on closeness of reference points. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 81, 616 – 626. Van den Bos, K., Wilke, H. A. M., & Lind, E. A. (1998). When do we need procedural fairness? The role of trust in authority. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 75, 1449 –1458. Van Prooijen, J.-W., De Cremer, D., Van Beest, I., Ståhl, T., Van Dijke, M., & Van Lange, P. A. M. (2008). The egocentric nature of procedural justice: Social value orientation as moderator of reactions to decision- making procedures. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 44, 1303–1315. Van Prooijen, J.-W., Gallucci, M., & Toeset, G. (2008). Procedural justice in punishment systems: Inconsistent punishment procedures have detri- mental effects on cooperation. British Journal of Social Psychology, 47, 311–324. 1179AUTONOMY AND PROCEDURAL JUSTICE Van Prooijen, J.-W., & Karremans, J. C., & Van Beest, I. (2006). Proce- dural justice and the hedonic principle: How approach versus avoidance motivation influences the psychology of voice. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 91, 686 – 697. Van Prooijen, J.-W., Van den Bos, K., Lind, E. A., & Wilke, H. A. M. (2006). How do people react to negative procedures? On the moderating role of authority’s biased attitudes. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 42, 632– 645. Van Prooijen, J.-W., Van den Bos, K., & Wilke, H. A. M. (2002). Procedural justice and status: Status salience as antecedent of procedural fairness effects. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 83, 1353–1361. Van Prooijen, J.-W., Van den Bos, K., & Wilke, H. A. M. (2004). Group belongingness and procedural justice: Social inclusion and exclusion by peers affects the psychology of voice. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 87, 66 –79. Van Prooijen, J.-W., Van den Bos, K., & Wilke, H. A. M. (2005). Procedural justice and intragroup status: Knowing where we stand in a group enhances reactions to procedural justice. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 41, 664 – 676. Van Prooijen, J.-W., Van den Bos, K., & Wilke, H. A. M. (2007). Procedural justice in authority relations: The strength of outcome de- pendence influences people’s reactions to voice. European Journal of Social Psychology, 37, 1286 –1297. Van Vugt, M., Hogan, R., & Kaiser, R. B. (2008). Leadership, follower- ship, and evolution. American Psychologist, 63, 182–196. Zuckerman, M., Porac, J., Lathin, D., Smith, R., & Deci, E. L. (1978). On the importance of self-determination for intrinsically motivated behav- ior. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 4, 443– 446. Received April 22, 2008 Revision received September 2, 2008 Accepted September 8, 2008 � 1180 VAN PROOIJEN work_jmscezihkndvpnedthgmb32uvm ---- A JOURNAL OF RELIGION AND INTERNATIONAL AFFAIRS worldview JUSTICE AND THE INTERNATIONAL COURT THE NEW STUDENT MOVEMENT TOM KAHN THE CHANGING SHAPE OF CONFLICT PHILIP M . KLUTZNICK WARS OF NATIONAL LIBERATION AND CHRISTIAN ETHICS THEODORE R. WEBER PAMPHILUS JULY-AUGUST 1966 VOL 9 NO. 7-8 In its decision of July 18, the International Court of Justice has declined to pass judgment on the case of South-West Africa. This profoundly dispiriting decision has made abun- dantly clear the difficulties of constructing a code of interna- tional conduct. Law has both a coercive and an educational function. The strongest and most realistic proponents of world peace through world law recognize that laws designed to reconcile conflict among nations will be ineffective unless there are procedures and institutions to enforce them. Laws that are proclaimed but continuaUy violated without stricture or reproach are of less than no value, for they make a mockery of what they purport to uphold. But to say this is not to state the entire case. For even when laws cannot be wholly or adequately enforced they can be of some instructive value—a value that can, hope- fully, increase. This would have been the case if the Inter- national Court had taken upon itself the task of passing judgment on a case which it had under consideration for years. The issue that was before the Court is of immense significance. In declining to rule, by a narrow decision and on narrow grounds, on whether South Africa had a continu- ing mandate for South-West Africa and whether, therefore, it could extend its policy of apartheid, the World Court exacerbated a dangerous situation and diminished its own stature. As Philip M. Klutznick says in this issue of worldview, South Africa "believes that it can continue to claim its place among the family of nations and still practice a vicious doc- trine, the demeaning concept of apartheid. . . . Yet it finds few, if any, in its anxious hour prepared to stand by its side." The World Court can hardly be said to stand by its side yet there can be no doubt that its ruling has cheered and bolstered the government of Prime Minister Verwoerd. There is no longer any legal justification for arguing that the United Nations, as the inheritor of supervisory functions of the League of Nations, has the right and obligation to assess and pass judgment on South Africa's efforts to enhance the welfare of South-West Africa. This means t h a t t h e legal justification has been sundered from w h a t is commonly held to be a moral responsibility. For the population of South- w e s t Africa is 85,000 white and 488,000 non- white, a n d apartheid—which keeps t h e whites firmly in control—is under judgment. If this decision exposes the weakness of the in the magazines Robert L. Holmes of the University of Rochester philosophy department answers those who challenge "the expression by churchmen of views critical of government policy in the area of international af- fairs" in an article prepared for the June 15 issue of Christian Century. Holmes concedes that per- haps "the churchman qua churchman should stick to his business, but the business of the churchman qua Christian—there is a difference here—is to ad- dress himself with all the power of his conviction to the most pressing problems of the day. . . . No human action, political or otherwise, is immune from possible moral evaluation, and for the Chris- tian there is no conceivable moral evaluation to which his religion is not directly relevant. "Kant once said, 'We do not enter church to serve God there: we do so in order to prepare ourselves to serve Him in our lives.' Surely if serving God in our live means anything at all it means that certain actions in relation to our fellow men are enjoined and others prohibited. To suppose otherwise is to insulate an ethical code from the very subject mat- ter to which it is supposed to apply. The relevant question is not whether Christianity enjoins, permits and prohibits various things in our conduct, but what in particular it so enjoins, permits and pro- hibits; not whether the New Testament law of love is to bo translated into terms applicable to human conduct, but how it is to be so translated. To leave this question unanswered—or worse yet, unasked— is to render Christianity a shallow and ingrown shadow of religion demanding little more of us than ritualistic piety. "But suppose the question is answered by grant- ing that churchmen may speak to issues concerning national policy, provided they confine themselves to 'general moral issues'?" the author asks. The judgment 2 ivorldvieiv World Court a n d t h e difficulty of establishing an international code of conduct, it also shows the need for t h a t code and an effective Court, For when the legal paths to justice are clogged or closed those w h o are militantly determined to reach t h a t goal will search out other paths. And in their efforts conflict will necessarily be height- ened before it is resolved. J.F. here is that the churchman is less knowledgeable than the statesman in the area of specific policy de- cisions. "This view is mistaken," Holmes contends. "For once it is conceded that the churchman can properly assess actual and possible general policies, he cannot consistently be denied the further right (and, I should argue, the duty) to concern himself with the morality of specific policies, One cannot condemn or condone a general principle without condemning or condoning the particular acts and decisions subsumable under it—a point as much of logic as of morality. " , . . Granted, principles sometimes conflict and incompatible judgments may claim equal prima facie warrant. But what this shows is not that actions in the particular case are exempt from the scrutiny of Christian conscience, but that they deserve all the more circumspect examination from the standpoint of Christian morality. And it will not do to plead that since those are times of crisis we must stand quietly behind the government no matter what our convictions. For if a government's policy should be morally wrong, the prosecution of that policy may in the long-run constitute a greater threat than the crises it was designed to m e e t , . . . " Colm Brogan views with deep concern the widen- ing audience being granted in England to "The Cath- olic Marxists," and the role of a "radical Catholic" magazine which circulates the views of this school of thought. In an article in the June 24 issue of the Spectator, Brogan notes that "the end of the Vati- can Council came as a deep relief to a multitude of Catholics who had been nearly swept off their feet by the wind of ecclesiastical change. They had been faced with more changes in four years than had hap- work_jnvlionbffdazk7lmfrma7e3ze ---- Laura Valentini Canine justice: an associative account Article (Accepted version) (Refereed) Original citation: Valentini, Laura (2014) Canine justice: an associative account. Political Studies, 62 (1). pp. 37- 52. ISSN 0032-3217 DOI: 10.1111/j.1467-9248.2012.01006.x © 2013 The Author. Political Studies © 2013 Political Studies Association This version available at: http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/63699/ Available in LSE Research Online: January 2016 LSE has developed LSE Research Online so that users may access research output of the School. Copyright © and Moral Rights for the papers on this site are retained by the individual authors and/or other copyright owners. Users may download and/or print one copy of any article(s) in LSE Research Online to facilitate their private study or for non-commercial research. You may not engage in further distribution of the material or use it for any profit-making activities or any commercial gain. You may freely distribute the URL (http://eprints.lse.ac.uk) of the LSE Research Online website. This document is the author’s final accepted version of the journal article. There may be differences between this version and the published version. You are advised to consult the publisher’s version if you wish to cite from it. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/journal/10.1111/(ISSN)1467-9248 http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9248.2012.01006.x http://www.psa.ac.uk/ http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/63699/ Canine Justice An Associative Account∗ Laura Valentini University College London Abstract: A prominent view in contemporary political theory, the ‘associative view’, says that duties of justice are triggered by particular cooperative relations between morally significant agents, and that ‘therefore’ principles of justice apply only among fellow citizens. This view has been challenged by advocates of global justice, who point to the existence of a world-wide cooperative network to which principles of justice apply. Call this the challenge from geographical extension. In this paper, I pose a structurally similar challenge to the associative view: the challenge from species extension. This says that the existing network of cooperation extends beyond the human species, to encompass some non-human animals, particularly domesticated dogs. In light of this, if one believes that (i) certain non-human animals are morally significant (i.e. objects of moral concern), and that (ii) justice applies to fellow cooperators, one should also hold that domesticated dogs are owed justice in much the same way our human fellow citizens are. I conclude by considering the implications of this argument for the associative view, and animal-rights theory. Introduction A prominent view in contemporary political theory says that duties of social justice apply only among fellow social cooperators. On this ‘relational’ or ‘associative’ view, people who stand in certain types of social relationships acquire a privileged moral status vis-à-vis one another, over and above the basic moral concern owed to ∗ I am grateful to the participants at the Manchester Metropolitan University Workshop on Political Theory and Animal Rights (Manchester, September 2010), and at the Queen’s College Symposium (Oxford, November 2010) for discussion. Special thanks are owed to Alasdair Cochrane (who patiently read multiple versions of the paper), Steve Cooke, Bob Goodin, Will Kymlicka (and his reading group on animal rights), Christian List, and the anonymous reviewers of this paper for their very detailed comments and helpful suggestions. The paper was written while I was a postdoctoral researcher at Princeton University (2009/10) and revised while I was a visiting fellow at the Swedish Collegium for Advanced Study in Uppsala (Fall 2011). I am grateful to both institutions for their support. 2 human beings as such. In particular, proponents of the associative outlook argue, people who cooperatively support the institutions of their own societies are, unlike others, entitled to social justice. This view, most prominently advocated by John Rawls (1971), has often been taken to entail a conservative stance on the scope of principles of justice. For (many) associativists, the reach of such principles is typically confined to domestic political communities, to the exclusion of distant strangers who do not qualify as fellow cooperators (Rawls 1971 and 1999, Sangiovanni 2007). This ‘narrow’ associativist view has been repeatedly challenged by advocates of global justice, who point to the globalized nature of today’s world as evidence for the existence of a world-wide cooperative network to which principles of justice should apply (see e.g. Beitz 1999 and Pogge 1989). We might call this challenge to narrow associativism the challenge from geographical extension. The challenge does not question the normative foundations of the associative view, but simply says that, consistently applied, the view delivers much more radical conclusions than many of its advocates have acknowledged. In the present paper, I pose a similar challenge to the narrow associative view, which we might call the challenge from species extension. This challenge says that taking the associative view seriously implies explicitly acknowledging that the morally relevant network of cooperation extends beyond the human species, to encompass at least some non-human animals. I make this case specifically with respect to domesticated dogs, though the logic of the argument could be extended to other animals too. In a nutshell, I argue that if one believes that (i) certain non- human animals are objects of moral concern and that (ii) justice applies to fellow cooperators (provided they are objects of moral concern), then one should also 3 believe that domesticated dogs are owed justice in much the same way our human fellow citizens are. The contribution of this paper is twofold, to animal ethics and to political theory. First, the paper illustrates how a relational approach to morality may apply to non- human animals, specifically in connection with the duties we owe them on grounds of justice. This is of value insofar as much advocacy of animals’ ethical status focuses on the type of creatures they are (i.e. sentient beings with lives to lead), rather than on the ways they relate to us.1 To be sure, some thought has already been given to the responsibility-generating character of special relations between humans and animals. However, emphasis on contextual relations is still relatively marginal in the literature and has been often accompanied by a rejection of the justice-based approach adopted here, in favour of what might be termed an ‘ethics of care’. Until recently, the key normative concern of ‘relational’ views has been not so much giving animals ‘their fair share’, but responding to their emotional and physical vulnerabilities2 (see, however, Coeckelbergh 2009 and especially Donaldson and 1 For instance, see the mission statements of the UK party Animals Count; The German Animal Protection Party, and the Dutch Party for the Animals. 2 Mary Midgley (1983) grounds animals’ moral status in their emotional abilities and capacity to create social ties with humans, with whom they share a ‘mixed community’. J. Baird Callicott (1992) defends a somewhat similar view, which emphasizes how our moral obligations towards domesticated animals radically differ from our obligations towards wild ones, which do not belong to our communities. For a critique of this perspective see Hadley (2007). Feminist defences of non- human animals’ moral standing have also focused on animals’ ability to feel emotions and their susceptibility to domination by humans (see Donovan and Adams 2007). For another relational view, according to which nonhuman animals are owed duties of help/assistance in virtue of their contextual vulnerability to, and dependence on, human beings, see Palmer (2010). Finally, Anderson (2004) defends a pluralist perspective on the moral status of non-human animals, with a particular emphasis on their social membership and relationships of reciprocity with humans. 4 Kymlicka 2011, for very important exceptions).3 Second, the paper shows that the associative account of justice, so prominent in contemporary political theory, has potentially radical implications, which its proponents have by and large failed to acknowledge, and which they might not want to accept. In sections 1 and 2, I explain the two basic premises of my argument: (i) non- human animals are objects of moral concern, and (ii) social justice is owed to fellow co-operators (provided they are objects of moral concern). In subsequent sections, I illustrate how, if these premises are endorsed, the nature of our relationship with domesticated dogs should lead us to conclude that they are owed justice as much as human fellow citizens are. Specifically, in section 3, I give a brief descriptive account of how relations between humans and dogs have evolved over millennia, and consider dogs’ role in modern society. I argue that most domesticated dogs are an integral part of our existing schemes of cooperation and are therefore entitled to more than the minimal concern all animals have a right to. In section 4, I offer a tentative account of what giving dogs their due requires. In section 5, I consider an important objection, and I then conclude with a few remarks on what the 3 Sue Donaldson and Will Kymlicka’s book, Zoopolis, was published when this article was nearing completion, and I am therefore unable to discuss it in detail. The book argues that the domestication of animals has created relations of membership that generate distinctive claims of justice. Specifically, Donaldson and Kymlicka (2011) apply liberal citizenship theory to the debate on animal rights, bringing notions such as ‘sovereignty, denizenship, migration, territory, membership and citizenship’ to bear on it (p. 14). Different animals, they suggest, relate to our societies in very different ways (e.g. as denizens, citizens, foreigners etc.), and this qualifies them as holders of correspondingly different sets of rights. To the extent that relationships of fellow citizenship are seen as relationships among fellow cooperators, the (much more comprehensive) approach Donaldson and Kymlicka defend is very much in line with the associative account I am exploring here. In both of our cases, there is an attempt to apply conceptual tools developed in another area of political philosophy (i.e. liberal global justice in my case, liberal citizenship theory in Donaldson and Kymlicka’s) to the debate on animal rights. 5 extensibility of duties of justice to non-human animals implies for the associative account itself. Before getting started, let me clarify that I do not aim to defend premises (i) and (ii) – about animals’ moral status and associative justice – but only to show that their conjunction, coupled with some empirical facts, has surprising implications for our thinking about justice and animals’ (specifically dogs’) entitlements. Since such premises are plausible and, in fact, widely endorsed, my lack of commitment to them should not undermine the contribution of the paper. 1. Non-human Animals as Objects of Basic Moral Concern The claim that we owe particular associative obligations to dogs presupposes not only an associative account of justice, but also the view that non-human animals (including dogs) are appropriate objects of moral concern in the first place. To see this, consider the following example. Although I am engaged in a sort of cooperative (perhaps exploitative) relation with my computer, the suggestion that by virtue of this relation I owe justice to it seems absurd. Why? Not because of a flaw in the associative perspective, but rather because my computer is not the sort of entity to which moral concern is owed, or at least so many would think.4 Animals, however, are unlike computers in that they are sentient creatures with lives to lead (Francione 2004). Although they lack the higher-order capacities for moral reasoning that would qualify them as subjects of moral responsibility, this does not automatically disqualify them as appropriate objects of moral concern 4 Some might disagree, however. For instance, Coeckelbergh (2009) thinks that an associative/contractarian perspective can be developed prescinding from intrinsicist claims about creatures’ fitness for having moral status. For this reason, he puts forward the interesting and controversial view that contractarian/associative justice extends even to plants and robots. 6 (Regan 1983). Within the human realm, we routinely distinguish moral responsibility from moral concern. Small children and the severely mentally disabled lack the necessary features to count as subjects of moral responsibility, but we regard them as worthy objects of moral concern. These kinds of observations have led many theorists to conclude that non-human animals count as members of the moral community. For instance, consequentialists have argued that animals’ sentience – their capacity to feel pain and pleasure – makes them appropriate objects of moral concern, whose well-being should be given weight in the moral evaluation of our actions (see e.g. Singer, 1990). Deontologists, on the other hand, have insisted that (at least some kinds of) non-human animals are appropriately regarded as bearers of fundamental rights (see e.g. Regan 1983 and Francione 2000). Since my primary focus here is on the associative approach to justice, and this approach is situated within a broadly liberal-deontological perspective, I more narrowly concentrate on deontological defences of animals’ moral status. I therefore interpret premise (i) of my overall argument – that animals are objects of moral concern – in deontological terms, whereby the relevant concern is expressed in the form of rights, and duties correlative to them. Different ethicists have focused on different characteristics exhibited by animals as the basis for granting them rights. Tom Regan (1983), for instance, has argued that to the extent that animals are conscious ‘subjects-of-a-life’, for whom things can go better or worse, they have inherent value and should therefore be regarded as right-holders. Francione (2000), by contrast, has grounded animal rights in animals’ sentience. Other animal-rights advocates, such as Rachels (1976), have placed 7 emphasis on animals’ having interests.5 For present purposes, I need not worry about these differences. Readers can simply choose the account they find most congenial. All I need to assume is a broad defence of animals’ entitlement to basic, non-relational moral concern. Granted that such a defence is available, what does this basic moral concern amount to? Two universal duties are generally acknowledged within deontological moral theories: a very stringent duty not to harm others, and a less stringent duty to help them when they are in need, provided this is not too costly to oneself (Rawls 1971, p. 114). These are ‘natural’ duties, which fall upon moral agents regardless of their voluntary actions or the particular relationships in which they stand vis-à-vis one another.   The duty not to harm is universal and correlative to a universal right not to be harmed. This means that every moral agent is under a duty not to harm (e.g. physically injure, steal from, harass) every other moral subject. In turn, every moral subject has an entitlement to not being harmed by any other moral agent. The duty to help the needy has a different structure. Although it is universal, i.e. it binds every moral agent, it is not correlative to a universal right. It is not the case that every moral agent is under a duty to help every other needy creature, a demand 5 Note that what follows from animal rights at the level of policy varies from theorist to theorist. Some animal-rights ethicists broadly subscribe to what is known as ‘abolitionism’, namely the view that the use of animals on the part of humans is morally unacceptable. See e.g. Regan (1983) and especially Francione (2000, 2010 with Garner). Other ethicists, however, are less drastic about the implications of conferring rights on non-human animals. See e.g. DeGrazia (1996 and 2002), and Rollin (1981). There are then those, like Garner (2010 with Francione), who adopt a more gradualist approach, and argue for the regulated and humane use of animals either per se, or as a fruitful strategy to achieve abolitionist goals. I thank an anonymous reviewer for suggesting to clarify this. For a general overview of the debate, from which I have learnt, see DeGrazia (1991). See also section 5, below, for further discussion of the implications of conferring rights on animals. 8 that would clearly be impossible to satisfy. Instead, when it comes to duties to help the needy, agents have a fair amount of discretion in determining when and how to discharge them. While breaching such duties clearly implies wrongdoing, it never amounts to a rights violation (O’Neill 1996, chap. 5).6 Since animals are objects of moral concern, they are addressees of the duty not to harm and of the duty to help. Crucially, these duties are baseline, non-relational duties and do not exhaust the realm of moral obligation. There are indeed many so- called special duties, correlative to rights, which we owe to specified others in particular and bear either by virtue of voluntary acts that we have performed – e.g. promises or contracts – or by virtue of the particular relations in which we stand vis- à-vis other people – e.g. our friends, families, colleagues etc. (see Hart 1955). For instance, a food supplier’s duty to deliver fresh produce on a daily basis is not correlative to a universal right, but only owed to those customers with whom he has signed a contract. Similarly, a mother’s duty to take care of, and protect, her children is owed to her children, and only to them. More broadly, family members or groups of friends have duties towards each other that they do not have towards anyone else, precisely by virtue of the special relationships in which they are involved. Notice that these special duties are not a mere specification of the natural duty to help those in need. Instead, they are duties correlative to rights which pertain to specific relations and are structurally similar to the duty not to harm. Like this duty, 6 Cf. the more general distinction between justice and beneficence. 9 special duties are very stringent and owed to particular individuals who have a right to their performance.7 As anticipated, a prominent strand within political philosophy argues that the enforceable duties of justice fellow citizens owe one another are of this weighty, relational, kind. This leads me to expound the second premise of the argument: the associative account of justice. 2. The Associative Account of Justice In contemporary liberal theorizing, the ‘associative’ account of justice is most commonly traced to John Rawls’s work. His principles of justice are said to apply to society understood as a ‘system of cooperation’ for the production and distribution of goods each citizen needs in order to lead a worthwhile life (Rawls 1971). On this associative account, we owe more to our fellow citizens than we owe to distant strangers because citizens are fellow cooperators within societal arrangements. Society provides the background conditions in which individuals can lead flourishing lives, and by working to sustain this background, each citizen is owed a ‘fair return’ for what he/she contributes. Principles of social justice enforced by the state are meant to provide this fair return (Sangiovanni 2007, esp. pp. 26-7). Unlike fellow citizens, distant strangers are not part of a joint collective enterprise, and are therefore owed only basic moral concern. Since we do not contribute to shaping the background conditions in which they live, so the argument goes, we owe them relatively little. (Of course, as I have already mentioned, this assumption is less and less tenable in an increasingly globalized world.) So long as 7 Indeed, we often characterize breaches of special duties in terms of harm. For instance, a mother who (culpably) fails to provide for her daughter’s subsistence may be said to harm her (McGrath 2005). But cf. Donaldson and Kymlicka (2011, Introduction). 10 we refrain from harming them, and help them when they are in need at reasonable costs, our behaviour towards them is beyond moral reproach (cf. Rawls 1999). The conclusions reached by the associative account in the case of international justice may strike some as unpalatable, but we can leave them aside for present purposes. What we need to establish is instead how ‘fair returns’ for social cooperation between members of the same political community are to be determined. To do so, liberals often resort to a ‘universal justifiability’ test. From a liberal point of view, schemes of social cooperation are fair (i.e. just), only to the extent that they are justifiable in the eyes of all those participating in them.8 Although it is difficult precisely to establish what would positively fulfil the requirement of universal justifiability, we can still confidently identify circumstances in which the requirement falls short of being satisfied. For instance, a society that fails to protect some of its citizens’ liberty, political, or economic rights is unlikely to qualify as a fair scheme of cooperation. How could it be justified to everyone participating in it? Agents whose fundamental rights are disregarded have no reason to join the would-be cooperative scheme. From their point of view, the scheme is exploitative and unacceptable. Their contribution to it is not properly acknowledged. That said, there may be multiple societal arrangements meeting the criterion of universal justifiability, especially when it comes to socio-economic justice. Different resource-distribution patterns, for instance, might meet a broad universal 8 Consider, for instance, Rawls’s (1971) original-position thought experiment, or T.M. Scanlon’s (1998) reasonable-rejectability test. For discussion of the original position in the context of animal rights see Rowlands (2002, ch. 3) and Hilden (2007). 11 justifiability test, provided each person has enough to lead a worthwhile life (see Rawls 1999 on ‘reasonably just’ societies, and Valentini 2011, pp. 173-8). For present purposes we need not settle these complex issues. All we need to assume is that a system of cooperation is fair to the extent that it is in principle acceptable in the eyes of all participants and that, even on a parsimonious account of what this requires, the obligations holding between fellow citizens are ‘thicker’ than standard natural duties. In particular, all fellow cooperators are entitled, vis-à-vis one another, to the social conditions necessary to lead decent lives. These will include at least liberty and political rights as well as rights to ‘sufficient’ economic resources.9 If some of the associates lack the objects of these rights, we can immediately infer that they are being treated unjustly. That is, they are not given fair returns for what they contribute.10 But what does the associative account imply for non-human animals? At first sight, one might say, not much. After all, non-human animals have their own habitats and cooperative relationships outside human society, and are therefore not appropriate recipients of associative justice. A moment’s reflection, though, shows that this conclusion would be too quick. At least some non-human animals, namely domesticated ones, are very much part of our lives within society, in some cases even as friends or family members. In light of this, should we think of them as 9 For those who find this last requirement too strong, it could be replaced with a right to meaningful opportunities for subsistence. 10 It might be objected that what counts as a ‘fair return’ should depend on what exactly each has contributed. On this view, the talented, hard-working and skilled deserve more than others. Proponents of the associative account, however, find this line of reasoning flawed. This is because one’s talents and skills, as well as the market rewards they command, are to a large extent products of the background social structure to which everyone contributes. In light of this, the justification for giving the skilled and talented higher returns considerably weakens. See Sangiovanni (2007, pp. 25- 6), cf. Rawls (1971). 12 fellow associates entitled to justice? In what follows, I answer this question specifically in relation to domesticated dogs (cf. Anderson 2004, p. 287). 3. Dogs and Human Beings: A History of Cooperation To substantiate the claim that dogs qualify as fellow cooperators, it is worth briefly sketching the history of their relations with humans (on this, I am indebted to McNeely and Lindquist 2007, pp. 101-4).11 This history is long, constantly evolving, and contested. Dogs are descendants of wolves, wild animals that live and hunt in packs. With the formation of the first human communities, wolves and humans came into contact and started to benefit from this connection. By living in the vicinity of humans, wolves were able to take advantage of food waste and unwanted leftovers as a source of nutrition, while humans could rely on wolves’ superior predatory instincts and benefit from their assistance in hunting (see Groves 1999). Those wolves that happened to be least aggressive and most docile were particularly successful at interacting with humans and gained the greatest selective advantage. They were best adapted to, and most preferred by, the humans they interacted with. Over generations, this led to an evolutionary process in which what used to be wolves became what we now call dogs. With the establishment of societies based mainly on farming and agriculture, humans began to use dogs no longer primarily in hunting but to transport heavy materials, defend their possessions, herd livestock, and so forth. More recently (arguably), humans also started to appreciate dogs simply for their companionship, 11 Like any reconstruction of human-dog relationships, the one I am about to offer is somewhat controversial. For instance, on some accounts, dogs were first adopted as companion animals, and only later used in hunting. Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pointing this out. 13 as reflected in the epithet of man’s ‘best friends’ (McNeely and Lindquist 2007, pp. 101-4). The history of cooperation between humans and dogs continues today. Dogs herd cattle, help walk the blind, guard our property, participate in rescue operations, work with the military and the police (among other things as sniffer dogs detecting illegal substances), assist in psychological therapies and are used in hospitals to relieve patients' anxiety.12 These appear to be tasks that warrant granting them the status of cooperating members of society. Dogs, it seems, have jobs and contribute to our societies’ functioning and prosperity in often obvious and direct ways. For this reason, shouldn’t they be given at least some of those rights and benefits that human citizens typically enjoy (mutatis mutandis)? Someone might object that talking of cooperation in the case of dogs is misleading.13 Cooperation only exists when different agents voluntarily come together to pursue a common goal. Our relationships to dogs, however, can hardly be said to fit this description. We are responsible for domesticating them, and we now use them in pursuit of our own goals. Dogs, therefore, are not cooperating members of society, instead, they are exploited members of society.14 True, human beings have turned wolves into domesticated dogs, and our objector might be right to suggest that there is something morally problematic about this original act of domestication (but cf. Groves 1999). But even so, dogs as we know them are very different from wolves and can no longer easily survive in the wild. 12 As the Australian Companion Animal Council (2009) states ‘Dogs serve us not only as companions but also as workers [... such as] guide dogs for the blind, hearing and assistance dogs for the disabled, sniffer dogs used by police and customs, and farm dogs used for stock work.’ 13 Thanks to Steve Cooke for raising this objection. The objection is broadly in line with the concerns expressed by so-called ‘abolitionists’. See note 5. 14 A similar objection is briefly raised and answered in Coeckelbergh (2009, p. 77). 14 They have become humanized in so many ways that, arguably, their natural habitat is human society. Abandoning a Chihuahua, a Dalmatian, or even a Great Dane into the woods would in all likelihood result in their death. From the fact that, due to our original act of domestication, dogs cannot but participate in our societies, does it also follow that their participation is intrinsically exploitative? It does not. To see this, consider an analogous case drawn from the human world. Imagine a capitalist society so far removed from other communities that citizens have no realistic opportunity to leave it, and in which free market forces determine the division of benefits and burdens of social cooperation. Lacking the necessary means to lead a decent life, workers in our society are forced to accept any job offers, even extremely unfair ones (see Cohen 1983). A society so organized would not be regarded as just from the perspective of any plausible liberal-deontological approach. Some of its members are obviously exploited, their cooperation is not appropriately rewarded. However, if the division of benefits and burdens were regulated by principles of justice, no exploitation would occur, and our society would appropriately qualify as a cooperative scheme (even though citizens would have no realistic opportunity to leave it). The case of dogs is not dissimilar from that of workers in the society I have just described. Dogs de facto cooperate and, like our workers, have little alternative to living in society. This, however, does not entail that their cooperation must be inevitably unfair or exploitative. In fact, the whole point of applying the associative account to dogs is to make sure that their cooperation is acknowledged and appropriately rewarded, so that our relations to them are not of an exploitative nature. That said, another objector might complain that only a relatively small number of dogs plausibly count as cooperating members of society. Most domesticated dogs 15 (literally millions of them) are mere companion animals, without proper ‘jobs’. Does this undermine the claim that dogs are fellow co-operators? I doubt so, for two reasons. First, from the liberal-deontological perspective assumed here, numbers cannot be given such moral weight. The (alleged) fact that only some dogs are cooperating members of society does not invalidate the claim that justice is owed to them. Second, and most importantly, the claim that only very few dogs cooperate in the required manner may be challenged by noting that having an officially recognized job is not a necessary condition to count as a productive member of society. Stay-at-home mothers and housewives are undoubtedly crucial for society’s prosperity and continued existence, yet they do not hold what were traditionally regarded as conventional ‘jobs’. As most now acknowledge, however, this should not prevent such women from being appropriately rewarded for their efforts in raising children and providing a healthy family environment. Doing otherwise would amount to unfair discrimination, if not full-blown exploitation (see Rawls 2000, pp. 162-8). Similarly, even dogs that are not classified as ‘working dogs’ provide a significant contribution to society’s prosperity and good functioning. As pointed out by the Australian Companion Animal Council (ACAC), companion ‘[d]ogs can help to lower stress, alleviate loneliness, improve health, and encourage people to exercise more and enjoy the outdoors. They improve feelings of safety – both in the home and in public places. Dogs act to break down the barriers in society, and help people to meet and make friends.’ Some of the functions described in the previous passage are often performed by professionals, such as personal trainers and psychotherapists. If they count as cooperating members of society, why should ‘companion’ dogs not also enjoy a similar status? After all, low stress, physical exercise, good social relationships, and 16 feelings of safety are all important components of a well-functioning social system.15 To the extent that dogs contribute to providing these goods, they should be appropriately rewarded. Of course, there may still be ‘difficult’ or ‘uncooperative’ dogs (cf. McNeely and Lindquist 2007). However, just as the existence of some humans who cannot cooperate in society (e.g. psychopaths or the severely disabled) does not disqualify human beings in general from the status of fellow cooperators, similarly the existence of problematic dogs should not make us blind to the fact that many dogs do in fact cooperate with us. In light of this, what enforceable protections and rights are commensurate with dogs’ status as cooperating members of society? 4. Canine Justice: Giving Dogs their Due As one writer puts it, ‘the domestic dog exists precariously in the no-man’s-land between the human and non-human worlds. It is an interstitial creature, neither person nor beast, forever oscillating uncomfortably between the roles of high-status animal and low-status person’ (Serpell 1995, p. 254 quoted in McNeely and Lindquist 2007, p. 104). Although there exist laws against cruelty towards non- human animals, including dogs, these are far from being fully reflective of their status as cooperating members of society. Indeed, as animal-rights advocates have long-been complaining, existing laws fall short of acknowledging animals’ status as right-holders in the first place. In what follows, I offer an illustrative account of what giving dogs their due as (i) right-holders and (ii) fellow cooperators demands.16 In doing so, my aim is to showcase the potential implications of the associative 15 For a survey of the benefits and harms of companion animals in general see Podberscek (2006). 16 This distinction is drawn for analytical purposes, and there is bound to be overlap between these two sets of requirements in the case of dogs (and cooperating animals more generally). 17 approach. I am aware, however, that a comprehensive treatment of the issue would require a much fuller discussion than I can provide here. 4.1 Dogs as Right-Holders in General17 First, dogs ought not to be regarded as mere property. By considering dogs as property, we implicitly treat them as objects, which may be used by their owners (see Hilden 2007, and Francione 2004). To be sure, as Cochrane (2009a), for instance, has pointed out, to the extent that the ownership relation is suitably qualified (i.e. to the extent that strict limits are imposed on how the object of ownership can be used), treating animals (including dogs) as property is morally acceptable. That is, so long as dog owners bear certain obligations towards their pets, the ownership relation cannot be so detrimental to them. There is no conceptual inconsistency in jointly claiming that (i) A owns X and that (ii) A has a duty of care towards X. This seems to be the view underlying the 2006 UK Animal Welfare Act (section 9), which explicitly establishes the responsibility of the pet owner to ‘take such steps as are reasonable in all the circumstances to ensure that the needs of an animal for which he is responsible are met to the extent required by good practice’. Although it is correct to point out that property relations do not per se preclude the possibility of treating animals as objects of moral concern, they do run counter their status as right-holders. Considering dogs a piece of property partly obscures their moral status, making the presumption that they are ‘things’ to be used more plausible (see Francione 2004). If dogs are mere property, then it is rhetorically easier to justify giving them to shelters, abandoning, and neglecting them. 17 The changes I propose under this heading are relatively familiar ones in the literature. In particular, my account here is indebted to Hilden (2007, pp. 19ff.). 18 This is reflected in the comparatively light forms of punishment risked by those who ignore their duties towards non-human animals in general, and dogs in particular. Even in the much-welcomed 2006 Act mentioned earlier, fines for neglect and cruelty towards non-human animals go up to just 20000 GBP, and periods spent in jail up to 51 weeks (BBC 2011). These sanctions appear strict if we conceptualize them as responses to failures to abide by duties towards one’s property. However, they appear much less demanding when we consider them as responses to rights violations. We would be shocked if the maximal penalty for killing or abusing a child amounted to just 51 weeks in jail. If we take seriously the idea that dogs qualify as holders of rights, current legislation seems excessively tolerant. To fully recognize dogs’ status as right-holders in our legal system, we must stop framing our relationship with them in terms of property (Hilden 2007, pp. 19-20). Needless to say, if dogs publically acquired the aforementioned status, many widespread practices currently considered acceptable, such as using them for meat consumption (in those countries where this is an accepted habit) or in scientific experimentation, would be outlawed. It is clear that such practices violate the ‘basic’ right not to be harmed, which, according to premise (i), non-human animals enjoy. As I have argued, however, dogs are also fellow associates and therefore recipients of justice (according to premise (ii)). What, then, do we owe them in this respect? 4.2 Dogs as Fellow Cooperators Entitled to Justice From a liberal perspective, associative justice requires respect for persons’ liberty, political, and economic rights. However, conferring on dogs the very same rights we typically ascribe to humans – such as the right to vote, to freedom of speech, to 19 education, to hold public office etc. – would be bizarre to say the least. In order to understand what giving dogs their due qua fellow cooperators demands, we cannot simply extend principles of justice for humans to the ‘canine’ realm. Instead, we need to consider how those principles are arrived at in the human case, and then ask whether a similar method could be adopted in the case of dogs.18 As we have seen, in contemporary liberal theory, principles of justice typically emerge from hypothetical consent tests. We look at society and ask: What principles could all citizens accept as giving them fair returns for their contributions? In other words, we ask: What principles could be justified in the eyes of all? As Jeremy Waldron says ‘...[liberal] commitments generate a requirement that all aspects of the social [order] should either be made acceptable or be capable of being made acceptable to every last individual’ (1987, p. 128). Although there may be reasonable disagreement about the exact output of some such thought experiment (e.g. on whether a society can only be just if it adopts Rawls’s difference principle), certain core liberty, political, and economic rights must be guaranteed for a political system to count as just. Indeterminacy, in this context, does not make us completely unable to say what justice demands. A sceptic might suggest that indeterminacy does become fatal when we move to hypothetical-consent tests in the case of dogs. Indeed, while we can imagine what is acceptable or not from the viewpoint of human beings in general, resorting to hypothetical consent in the case of non-human animals might seem pointless, ‘suggesting no clear scenario that would assist our thinking’ (Nussbaum 2004, p. 301). It is sometimes hard to put oneself into other people’s shoes, let alone into the 18 This is a ‘logic of extension’ mirroring the one often used, mutatis mutandis, in the debate on global justice. 20 ‘paws’ of creatures belonging to another species (see Hilden 2007, part II and Rowlands 2002 for critiques of this argument). This is a warranted worry, but not one that undermines the project of making sense of what it is to give dogs their due qua cooperating members of society. Even though it is hard, perhaps impossible, to gain profound knowledge of a dog’s psychology, of its deepest beliefs and desires, we can still form a reasonably clear picture of what conditions must be satisfied for dogs to lead decent lives. Dogs cannot ‘directly’ speak their minds, but their behaviour can be interpreted, and their interests reasonably inferred from it, and from their biological makeup more generally (Donaldson and Kymlicka 2011, pp. 108-12, Rowlands 2002, pp. 66-8, Hilden 2007 pp. 17ff.). This is not to deny that, since dogs do not belong to our species, their needs and interests are bound to remain somewhat opaque to us. But opacity is not the same as inscrutability, and so long as we can at least partly understand dogs’ interests, we ought to provide them with the necessary conditions to lead decent lives on grounds of justice. That is, society should be organized in such a way that not only human beings, but also dogs, could consent to it. For example, we can reasonably assume that, like children, dogs have an interest in generating social bonds of affection as members of a pack or family. They have an interest in bodily integrity and freedom from violence, as well as in having access to food, shelter, and medical care. They have an interest in enjoying sexual pleasure, and in living in an environment where they can move reasonably freely (cf. Nussbaum 2004, pp. 313-17). These are all interests we can plausibly assume dogs have, and which would have to be secured for dogs to consent to living in society, if they could. 21 Of course, making our societies more sensitive to dogs’ needs is a hard task to accomplish. In what follows, I only offer some candidate examples of the sorts of reforms that ought arguably to be undertaken to realize ‘canine justice’.19 To begin with, since there is a strong correlation between the satisfaction of dogs’ interests (in bodily integrity, nutrition, health care etc.) and the families of which dogs become members, those who wish to adopt a puppy (or an adult dog) should be adequately checked. In the same way in which young children are only entrusted to families deemed capable of caring for them, so too dogs should only be entrusted to humans deemed capable of providing them with a healthy and safe environment (cf. Hilden, pp. 21-2). However, to make sure that ‘human guardians’ adequately take account of their dogs’ interests, broader social changes are required, setting limits to what is deemed acceptable animal treatment. For instance, seemingly harmless habits, such as having one’s dog compete in a beauty contest, can be revealing of, or conducive to, a problematic ‘commodifying attitude’ towards the animal, with detrimental effects on its health and bodily integrity. For example, there is little doubt that ‘plastic surgery’ performed on dogs, in the from of ear-cropping and tail-docking, is very often motivated by human perceptions of beauty which have little to do with dogs’ own well-being. In recognition of this, the 2006 UK Animal Welfare Act (sections 5 and 6) has precisely banned such practices.20 Similarly, the search for purity of breed, to ensure that dogs meet specified aesthetic standards, is often harmful to the health and well- 19 For a more general and comprehensive discussion of what treating domesticated animals as citizens would require, see Donaldson and Kymlicka (2011, sec. 5.4). 20 Specifically, the Act bans cutting dogs’ tails for cosmetic reasons, but not in the case of ‘working dogs’. 22 being of the animal itself.21 Moreover, a concern with dogs’ bodily integrity and their interest in experiencing sexual pleasure would plausibly lead to banning permanent sterilization – although I venture the hypothesis that non-invasive contraceptive methods might be used for birth-control purposes (but cf. Fusfeld 2007 for a different view). A ‘caninely just’ society should not only ban social practices that are explicitly harmful to dogs, but also make sure that the environment in which they live is sufficiently hospitable to them. This requires attention at the level of urban planning, making sure that dogs have access to designated areas protected from traffic in which to move freely, socialize, and play (ACAC 2009). Finally, dogs’ interests should be given official representation within society, so as to secure their protection over time. Although, as mentioned earlier, dogs cannot be given the right to vote or to hold public office, appointed representatives may act on their behalf at both the political and the legal level, making sure that their status as objects of moral concern is adequately defended (see Garner 2005, Nussbaum 2004 and Hilden 2007). More could be said, but if at least some of these arguments are correct, we can conclude that giving dogs their due would involve some relevant changes in the way society is organized. This, in itself, should come as no surprise. Indeed, perhaps even more significant changes appear to be needed when we think about what a ‘humanly’ just society requires. There is a big gap between most societies in the world and the ideal of a just social system liberal political philosophers advocate. 21 On this, see the work of The Royal Society for the Prevention of Cruelty to Animals (RSPCA), http://www.rspca.org.uk/allaboutanimals/pets/dogs/health/pedigreedogs/actions and http://www.rspca.org.uk/media/news/story/-/article/PuppiesBredForLooksAreBornToSuffer_Dec11 (last accessed 3/10/2012). 23 In connection with this, it is crucial to emphasize that the ‘caninely just’ society envisaged in this paper is an example of an ‘ideal-theoretic’ scenario (Rawls 1971, pp. 8-9, and Simmons 2010 for discussion). In the same way in which change towards a more just society for humans takes time, change towards a more just society for dogs (let alone other animals) is also a matter of long and gradual reform.22 The policies discussed here could not be implemented straightaway, in our non-ideal world. For instance, in an ideal world, no dog would have to be euthanized in shelters because of overpopulation. However, it may well be that, due to the constraints of the non-ideal world in which we live (where too many dogs are abandoned, and where too little is invested in shelters) euthanizing some dogs might be a sadly inevitable solution, at least in the short term. Or else, in an ideal world, dogs would not need to be permanently sterilized. However, as a transitional, non- ideal measure for the world in which we live, permanent sterilization might be the best we can do to safeguard dogs’ interests. Unless alternative contraception methods are introduced as a way of ensuring birth control, the number of undesired and neglected animals will only increase. Even though a society that gives dogs their due is still a somewhat distant ideal, and many non-ideal measures would have to be undertaken to reach it, we might want to ask whether such a ‘caninely just’ society would inevitably result in greater injustice for humans. Although I am in no position to provide a well-grounded, conclusive answer to this question, I think there are some reasons for optimism. Many of the reforms that would make society more just for humans would also make it more just for dogs, and vice versa. 22 Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for asking me to elaborate on this point, and suggesting some of the examples that follow. 24 As I have mentioned earlier, sensitivity to dogs’ interests would have an impact on urban planning, increasing the number of parks and recreational areas sheltered from traffic available to both animals and humans. Similarly, a more just society for humans, in which everyone has adequate opportunities to lead a decent life, would in all likelihood be ‘friendlier’ towards dogs too. In such a society, the levels of violence, poverty and frustration among the general population would be lower than in the status quo, thereby reducing the risk for dogs themselves to be mistreated, subjected to violence, or simply neglected. In short, it appears reasonable to conjecture that human and canine justice would work together in synergy. After all, on the associative account, a society that is just to dogs and humans is, by definition, mutually beneficial for both.23 5. Objection In this section, I consider an important challenge to the account presented here. The challenge points to a perceived tension between the two main premises of the argument: (i) animals are objects of moral concern and (ii) justice applies to fellow cooperators (provided they are objects of moral concern). The worry is that, once we grant animals a set of rights on deontological grounds – in accordance with premise (i) – we are immediately led to embrace an ‘animal liberation’ perspective according to which cooperative relations between humans and animals violate those very rights. If the relationship of cooperation ends – as recommended by premise (i) under the present demanding interpretation – the associative account implies that 23 Notice that this conjecture is once again stated at the level of ‘ideal theory’. There are of course trade-offs to make in the status quo, where human and animal interests have to be balanced against each other. This is an extremely complex question I cannot address here. For discussion see Cochrane (2007) and Aaltola (2005). 25 animals ‘liberated’ from human dominion fall outside the scope of justice. This, in turn, amounts to the counter-intuitive view that animals are owed justice only when they are being exploited.24 This objection is based on a radical reading of the implications of premise (i) and an equivocation between exploitation and cooperation.25 While it is certainly true that conferring rights on animals prohibits us from treating them merely as means, it does not prevent us from treating them as means, provided we also treat them as ends in themselves.26 This is a familiar thought from the Kantian-deontological tradition and is clearly in line with what we consider morally acceptable treatment of other humans. Consider the relationship between a professor, Martin, and his research assistant, Bob. It is clear that, by giving Bob a set of calculations to perform, Martin uses him as a means to something: the results he needs for the paper he is writing. However, provided Martin treats Bob with respect, does not overburden, threaten, or grossly underpay him, we have reason to regard their relationship as perfectly morally acceptable. Martin treats Bob as a means but, crucially, also as an end in himself. By contrast, the relationship between a (non-benevolent) master and his slaves, or between the owner of an aggressive multinational corporation and his sweatshop workers, is morally objectionable precisely because the former use the latter as means, without also treating them as ends in themselves. What is going on in these 24 I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for raising this objection. 25 For an argument that animal rights need not imply animal ‘liberation’, see Cochrane (2009b). 26 This is indeed in line with the original formulation of Kant’s categorical imperative. Although, interestingly, when adopted to characterize the animal-rights position, this formulation at times loses the qualification ‘merely’, thus turning into an absolute ban on using others (including animals) as means. See e.g. Sunstein (2004, p. 5). 26 cases is exploitation, rather than cooperation (recall my earlier discussion of a capitalist society). Similarly, conferring rights on dogs does not automatically prevent us from engaging in cooperation with them, provided such cooperation is fair and non- exploitative, i.e. provided we treat them not merely as means, but also as ends in themselves. Much of this paper has been precisely concerned with sketching what this might require. Moreover, the claim that ‘absent relationships of cooperation, animals are not owed justice’ is not at all counter-intuitive if we keep in mind that justice does not exhaust the space of moral obligation. Wild animals, with which we entertain no cooperative relations, still maintain a right not to be harmed, and a right to assistance. Humans should therefore refrain from killing or injuring wild animals, and from destroying their natural habitats.27 Similarly, humans are under a duty to assist wild animals, when they can help them at reasonable costs.28 What wild animals do not have a right to, on the associative account, is a fair share in their cooperative endeavours with us, and this is simply because they are not fellow cooperators. While Swedes certainly have duties not to harm Australians, and to help them if they are in need, we typically do not think that Australians are entitled to Swedish health care or education. Why is that? The answer given by the associative account is: ‘because they are not part of the same society-wide scheme 27 This should be qualified by adding ‘unless they are posing an immediate threat to their own lives and well being’. 28 This does not imply that we are under a duty constantly to search for wild animals in need (as we are not under any such duty in the case of human beings). Moreover, this does not mean that we should try to save preys from their predators. This sort of interference could not count as a way of discharging the duty to help. By helping the prey, we would end up harming the predator. Cf. Cochrane (2009b, pp. 675-6), Callicott (1992). Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pushing me to clarify this point. 27 of cooperation as the Swedes, and are thus not entitled to a fair share of its benefits’ (Sangiovanni 2007, pp. 31-2). If one thinks that this stance is reasonable enough in the case of human beings (again, suspending complications due to globalization), there is no apparent reason why one should not think of it as reasonable in that of animals. In sum, a belief in animal rights – as per premise (i) – does not make fair cooperation between humans and animals impermissible, and allows us to show appropriate moral concern towards animals even when they exist outside our cooperative schemes. Conclusion I have explored the question of what, if anything, might be owed to non-human animals from the perspective of a popular, associative account of justice. Focusing on dogs in particular, I have suggested that justice requires their interests to be taken into account in the design of laws and policies within our political communities. Beyond this specific conclusion about the moral status of domesticated dogs, the paper has broader implications for both the debate on animal rights, and that on the associative account of justice. Regarding the former, by showing how an associative perspective can be extended to the case of non-human animals, the paper represents one of the few attempts, within justice theory, to consider what we might owe non- human animals for reasons which go beyond their intrinsic properties (for other such attempts, see Coeckelbergh 2009, and most importantly, Donaldson and Kymlicka 2011). Although I have not explicitly addressed the question of what might be owed to non-human animals other than dogs, the paper still offers a general method (hypothetical consent test) that could be applied to the case of other ‘cooperating’ animals as well. Of course, doing so will present a number of challenges and will 28 demand a fairly radical shift in people’s attitudes towards animals. There are in fact pervasive forms of human-animal ‘would-be cooperation’, such as meat farming, which fail to acknowledge the very status of animals as right-holders. That said, while the systematic and unnecessary killing of animals for food might be impermissible on the view presented here, humane cattle farming for dairy production (if feasible) might constitute a morally acceptable form of cooperation: cattle provide milk in return for shelter, fresh pastures, and care (see Hilden 2007, p. 24, but cf. Donaldson and Kymlicka 2011, pp. 138-9). Although I do not have the space to explore these arguments in detail, the associative approach presented here points in the direction of a balanced and intuitively appealing position, which despite emphasizing animal rights, avoids the extremism of abolitionist animal ethics. The paper also has implications for the debate on the associative account of justice. As I have mentioned at the outset, this account is often thought to entail a rather conservative stance on the scope of our duties of justice, especially with respect to their extension to the global realm. But what about the extension of justice to other species, rather than to citizens of other states? Interestingly, proponents of the associative account have by and large neglected this question. As this article has shown, however, such a cross-species extension is in principle possible. In fact, if we consider how many species are integrated, and used, within our social systems (arguably cats, dogs, horses, cattle, sheep, and so forth), we can immediately see that the implications of the associative account are potentially very radical indeed (cf. Donaldson and Kymlicka 2011). Whether proponents of this account would accept them is doubtful. However, what this article suggests is that these are implications they must reckon with. 29 REFERENCES Aaltola, E. (2005) ‘Animal Ethics and Interest Conflicts’, Ethics and the Environment, 10 (1), 19-48. ACAC, Australian Companion Animal Council, ‘Dogs in Society Position Paper’, http://www.acac.org.au/pdf/dogs_in_society.pdf (last accessed on 19/10/2011). Anderson, E. (2004) ‘Animal Rights and the Values of Non-human life’, in M. Nussbaum and C. Sunstein (eds), Animal Rights: Current Debates and New Directions. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 277-98. Animal Protection Party (1993) ‘Manifesto’, available online at http://www.tierschutzpartei.de/GSPtierschutz01.htm (last accessed 15/4/2011). Animals Count (2006) ‘Manifesto’, available online at http://www.animalscount.org/manifesto/aims/ (last accessed 15/4/2011). Animal Welfare Act (UK, 2006) available online at http://www.legislation.gov.uk/ukpga/2006/45/contents (last accessed 30/9/2012). BBC (2011) ‘Animal Welfare Law in the UK’, online http://www.bbc.co.uk/ethics/animals/overview/latest.shtml (last accessed 15/9/ 2011). Callicott, J. Baird (1992) ‘Animal Liberation and Environmental Ethics: Back Together Again’, in E.C. Hargrove (ed.), The Animal Rights/Environmental Ethics Debate. New York: State University of New York Press, pp. 249-61. Cochrane, A. (2007) ‘Animal Rights and Animal Experiments: An Interest-Based Approach’, Res Publica, 13 (3), 293-318. Cochrane, A. (2009a) ‘Ownership and Justice for Animals’, Utilitas, 21 (4), 424-42. Cochrane, A. (2009b) ‘Do Animals Have an Interest in Liberty?’, Political Studies, 57 (3), 660-79. 30 Coeckelbergh, M. (2009) ‘Distributive Justice and Co-Operation in a World of Humans and Non-Humans: A Contractarian Argument for Drawing Non-Humans into the Sphere of Justice’, Res Publica, 15 (1), 67-84. Cohen, G.A. (1983) ‘The Structure of Proletarian Unfreedom’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 12 (1), 3-33. DeGrazia, D. (1991) ‘The Moral Status of Animals and Their Use in Research: A Philosophical Review’, Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, 1 (1), 40-70. DeGrazia, D. (1996) Taking Animals Seriously: Mental Life and Moral Status. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. DeGrazia, D. (2002) Animal Rights: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Donaldson S., and Kymlicka, W. (2011) Zoopolis: A Political Theory of Animal Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Donovan, J., and Adams, C.J. (2007) The Feminist Care Tradition in Animal Ethics. New York: Columbia University Press. Francione, G. (2000) Introduction to Animals Rights: Your Child or the Dog? Philadelphia: Temple University Press. Francione, G. (2004) ‘Animals – Property or Persons?’, in M. Nussbaum and C. Sunstein (eds) Animal Rights: Current Debates and New Directions. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Francione, G., and Garner, R. (2010) The Animal Rights Debate: Abolition or Regulation? New York: Columbia University Press. Fusfeld, L. (2007) ‘Sterilization in an Animal Rights Paradigm’, Journal of Animal Law and Ethics, 2, 255-62. Garner, R. (2005) The Political Theory of Animal Rights. Manchester: Manchester University Press. 31 Groves, C. (1999) ‘The Advantages and Disadvantages of Being Domesticated’, Perspectives in Human Biology, 4 (1), 1-12. Hadley, J. (2007) ‘Critique of Callicott’s Biosocial Moral Theory’, Ethics & the Environment, 12 (1), 67-78. Hart, H.L.A. (1955) ‘Are There Any Natural Rights?’, Philosophical Review, 64 (2), 175-91. Hilden, J. (2007) ‘A Contractarian View of Animal Rights: Insuring Against the Possibility of Being a Non-human Animal’, Animal Law Review, 14 (1), 5-28. McGrath, S. (2005) ‘Causation by Omission: A Dilemma’, Philosophical Studies, 123 (1-2), 125-48. McNeely, C.A. and Lindquist S.A. (2007) ‘Dangerous Dogs Laws: Failing to Give Man’s Best Friend a Fair Shake at Justice’, Journal of Animal Law, 3, 99-158. Midgley, M. (1983) Animals and Why They Matter. Athens: University of Georgia Press. Nussbaum, M. (2004) ‘Beyond “Compassion and Humanity”: Justice for Nonhuman Animals’, in M. Nussbaum and C. Sunstein (eds) Animal Rights: Current Debates and New Directions. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 299-320. O’Neill, O. (1996) Towards Justice and Virtue: A Constructive Account of Practical Reasoning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Palmer, C. (2010) Animal Ethics in Context. New York: Columbia University Press. Party for the Animals (2002) ‘Aims’, available online at http://www.partyfortheanimals.info/content/view/300 (last accessed 15/9/2011). Podberscek, A.L. (2006) ‘Positive and Negative Aspects of Our Relationship with Companion Animals’, Veterinary Research Communications, 30 (1), 21-7. 32 Rachels, J. (1976/1989), ‘Why Animals Have a Right to Liberty’, in T. Regan and P. Singer (eds), Animal Rights and Human Obligations. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall, pp. 122-31. Rawls, J. (1971) A Theory of Justice, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Rawls, J. (1999) The Law of Peoples, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Rawls, J. (2000) Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press. Regan, T. (1983) The Case for Animal Rights. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Rollin, B. (1981) Animal Rights and Human Morality. Buffalo: Prometheus Books. Rowlands, M. (2002) Animals Like Us. London: Verso. Sangiovanni, A. (2007) ‘Global Justice, Reciprocity, and the State’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 35 (1), 3-39. Scanlon, T.M., (1998) What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge MA: Belknap/Harvard. Serpell, J. (1995) The Domestic Dog: Its Evolution, Behaviour and Interactions with People. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Simmons, A. J. (2010) ‘Ideal and Nonideal Theory’, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 38 (1), 5-36. Singer, P. (1990) Animal Liberation. New York: Avon, 2nd ed. Sunstein, C. R., ‘Introduction: What Are Animal Rights?’, in M. Nussbaum and C. Sunstein (eds), Animal Rights: Current Debates and New Directions. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 3-18. Valentini, L. (2011) Justice in a Globalized World: A Normative Framework. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 33 Waldron, J. (1987) ‘Theoretical Foundations of Liberalism’, The Philosophical Quarterly, 37 (147), 127-50. Valentini_Canine justice_2016_cover Valentini_Canine justice_2016_author work_jpmzjajpergzllxeh2px2aezkq ---- Untitled A Kantian conception of global justice HELGA VARDEN* Abstract. I start this article by addressing Kant’s question why rightful interactions require both domestic public authorities (or states) and a global public authority? Of central importance are two issues: first, the identification of problems insoluble without public authorities, and second, why a domestic public monopoly on coercion can be rightfully established and maintained by coercive means while a global public monopoly on coercion cannot be established once and for all. In the second part of the article, I address the nature of the institutional structure of individual states and of the global authority. Crucial here, I argue, is Kant’s distinction between private and public right. Private right concerns rightful relations between individual legal subjects, where public right concerns legal subjects’ claims on their public institutions. I propose that the distinction between private and public right should be central to liberal critiques of current legal and political developments in the global sphere. Helga Varden is Assistant Professor in the Department of Philosophy and in Women and Gender Studies at the University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign. Her main research interests are in legal, political, and feminist philosophy, with a particular emphasis on Kantian and Lockean political philosophy. Her most recent publications include ‘Kant’s Non-Absolutist Conception of Political Legitimacy’, Kant-Studien; ‘Kant’s Non-Voluntarist Conception of Political Obligations: Why Justice is Impossible in the State of Nature’, Kantian Review; ‘The Lockean ‘Enough-and-as-Good’ Proviso – an Internal Critique’, Journal of Moral Philosophy; and ‘Kant’s murderer at the door . . . One More Time: Kant’s Legal Philosophy and Lies to Murderers and Nazis’, The Journal of Social Philosophy; ‘Lockean Freedom and the Proviso’s Appeal to Scientific Knowledge’, Social Theory and Practice. Introduction Why do we need an international authority like the United Nations (UN)? There is no doubt that the UN often fails, that it is ine!cient, and that it su"ers from corruption. So rather than seeking to reform and improve it, why not just follow the current trend of powerful nations, namely simply to set aside the UN and pursue unilateral solutions instead? Indeed, recently we have witnessed the US, a Western, liberal constitutional democracy, pursuing unilateralism in new ways. The US has employed private companies1 to perform security functions as part of * Thanks to the audience at the conference ‘International Law and Global Justice’, The Centre for the Study of Social Justice and the Centre for International Studies, University of Oxford (20–21 May 2009), Tiziana Torresi, Laura Valentini, Shelley Weinberg, Howard L. Williams, and an anonymous referee (RIS) for their useful comments on earlier versions of this article. 1 Blackwater Worldwide, DynCorp International and Triple Canopy. Review of International Studies (2011), 37, 2043–2057 ! 2011 British International Studies Association doi:10.1017/S0260210511000301 First published online 17 Oct 2011 2043 conducting a war as well as established prisons outside its own territory, in which presumed international criminals are held captive, subjected to military tribunals and punished – allegedly without being deprived of their human rights. Against these practices and others of their kind, many liberal voices have argued that we need an international body like the UN to be the sole authority regarding international interactions and interventions. Although liberals typically are critical of such unilateral practices in inter- national a"airs, it is unclear exactly why they think we need the UN. This is especially unclear on the assumption that states are not adhering to the realist paradigm, according to which the goal of foreign policy, primarily, is to attain ‘power, prestige, and wealth’ – to use John Rawls’s famous formulation.2 The lack of a clear answer to the question why we need the UN if states act according to just principles seems characteristic of ‘statist’ liberal positions, such as Rawls’s theory, ‘cosmopolitan theories’, such as those of Charles Beitz, Thomas Pogge, and Kok-Chor Tan, and ‘institution-based’ accounts such as the one defended by Allen Buchanan. Instead, these theories rest on the implied assumption that the UN is a prudential solution to problems of justice; it is simply easier to realise justice through it. If so, however, then these liberal thinkers should not be dissatisfied with the current debate’s focus on whether the US and its allies or the UN is more likely to be successful policing the world. And yet these liberal thinkers are typically uneasy about the prospect of particular states unilaterally assuming the role of a world police. But to justify their dissatisfaction with the status quo, liberal thinkers must say something about the special standing a global authority ought to have in transnational a"airs. Liberal thinkers must, but unfortunately do not, say something about what gives the UN special standing in global matters, such that that standing justifies an authoritative role. A general problem characterising much contemporary liberal thought is therefore that it does not clarify whether respect for human rights and global justice necessarily requires a global, public authority, rather than one, or more, just and powerful agent, such as a state. To bring clarity to this issue, what we need is an explicit answer to the following question: if we assume a world in which resources were plentiful and individuals and/or states were acting in accordance with just principles, would we still need a global political authority like the UN? Contemporary liberal accounts of justice typically do not provide an explicit answer to this question. In this article, I address this lacuna in contemporary liberal thought. The aim is to provide a Kantian account of the foundations of a liberal theory of global justice, namely a conception of the global public authority that reconciles statist concerns for the sovereignty of nations and cosmopolitan concerns for individual rights. In doing so, I outline a positive account of why global justice requires states and private persons not only to adhere to some reasonable conception of rightful transnational interaction, but also to establish a global public institutional authority to regulate their interactions. If it can be shown that there are problems characterising global interaction that cannot in principle be solved without appeal to a public authority, then it is incorrect to think that establishing global institutions is in principle unnecessary to enable just global interaction. In addition, contrary to common liberal assumptions, I argue 2 John Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Harvard University Press, 1999), p. 28. 2044 Helga Varden that the rights of public authorities go beyond those of private persons, meaning that the rights of public institutions are not coextensive with private persons’ rights against one another. Rethinking these core assumptions concerning the need for public institutions as well as the distinction between private persons’ rights and rights of public authorities are essential to showing how the Kantian approach can reconcile central concerns of both statist and cosmopolitan liberal theories of global justice without thereby arguing for a world state. I do not, however, want merely to take seriously the important insights from prominent liberal accounts. I aim for an account that takes seriously the current legal and political reality, understood primarily in historical and current develop- ments in international private and public law. My method is therefore informed by the idea that the most promising approach to global justice is able to critique actual, current developments in liberal law and political systems. The reason for this is neither merely that I want to avoid building a ‘castle in the air’ – beautiful to look at, but utterly useless for any practical purposes – nor simply that I believe that though often highly problematic in particular instances, there is wisdom in time worn liberal legal practices and the additions these practices push for as our world changes. This is also not to say that I find legal practices to be as wise and unproblematic as legal positivists often do. Rather, a liberal theory of justice should be able to illuminate whatever wisdom there is in liberal legal and political systems and use this knowledge to identify and engage the particular institutions comprising the actual systems. In particular, central to liberal legal and political systems is both the idea of individuals’ rights as well as a fundamental distinction between private and public right, where private right concerns rightful relations between private individuals, whereas public right concerns legal subjects’ claims on public institutions. This distinction, I believe, is one that neither is currently utilised by liberal theories of justice nor one that legal positivists make good sense of – whether we are focusing on issues of domestic justice or global justice. Yet it is a central distinction in the legal and political reality to which our theories should apply.3 Following Kant I will suggest that the distinction between private and public right is at the heart of a liberal critique of current legal and political developments, and hence essential as we try to identify both our current mistakes and the way forward in our institution building attempts. This article then, has two parts. Part one addresses the first question emphasised above, namely why rightful interactions – or interactions consistent with, ultimately, individuals’ right to freedom – require both domestic public authorities (states) and a global public authority. Of central importance here are two issues: first, the identification of which kinds of questions appear insoluble without public authorities, and second, explaining why a global public authority must be established, maintained, and developed through voluntary means even though a domestic authority can be rightfully established by coercive means. A global public authority is something that each party in the process can indepen- dently hope or wish for, but its establishment is something we can only intend collaboratively. This argument for the necessity of public authorities as well as the 3 Ingeborg Maus, in ‘From Nation-State to Global State, or the Decline of Democracy’, trans. James Ingram, Constellations: An International Journal of Critical & Democratic Theory, 13:4 (2006), pp. 465–84, also draw the attention this legal distinction when interpreting Kant’s conception of global justice. A Kantian conception of global justice 2045 principled di"erence between the rightful establishment of domestic and global public authorities, I propose, can explain important features of the current structure of domestic and international private right. The second part of the article turns to the nature of the institutional structure of both domestic and global public authorities. I briefly outline how domestic public right secures and enables private right for all of its citizens and how public right also contains other systemic measures involved in securing each citizen’s right to freedom. I then outline core similarities and di"erences with regard to international public right. My proposal is that in the future international public right will aim to secure and establish international private right for all even though its current main focus lies in establishing the other aspect of public right, namely public institutions as required to secure global systemic justice. Moreover, I argue that the development of international public right both as required to secure international private right and to secure global systemic justice demands that we do not give up on, but keep reforming the UN institutions. Finally I argue that the global public authority will only seek to maintain a voluntary peacekeeping force as needed to protect stateless persons and that it will only authorise coercion on behalf of its members towards aggressive states. Yet since only the global public authority can have rightful standing in interstate conflicts, the rightful solution also to transnational injustice goes through it. States resorting to unilateral military action is always the last resort – and one that is not, in principle, reconcilable with rightful global relations. Public authorities: why we need them The lack of reflection upon the status of a global political authority probably results from the fact that contemporary liberal theoretical analyses typically see all issues of justice – domestic or global – through the perspective of hypothetical consent. Much contemporary liberal theory seems implicitly to adopt the Lockean assumption of a prudential need for authoritative public institutional solutions to problems of interactions. Yet in contrast to the Lockeans, much liberal theory then takes a shortcut by arguing that what matters for justice is simply that the right principles are enforced without also addressing the question of whether and why it matters who gets to enforce them. True, liberal statist theories do assume that just states should enforce international laws; cosmopolitan theories simply identify the bottom line as the principle that human rights should be universally enforced; whereas institution-based theories emphasise the importance of institution building. Yet all these theories say little about why we need a distinctly public authority to specify, apply and enforce principles of global justice.4 Answering this question will 4 For example, it is unclear whether the realisation of Rawls’s ‘Society of Peoples’, which proposes a statist response to questions of global justice, necessarily involves the establishment of a public global authority of sorts or whether it is in principle su!cient that each one of the states (‘liberal’ and ‘decent’ peoples) individually abides, in its foreign policies, by the liberal principles (ideas and ideals) as put forward in the Law of Peoples. (See Rawls, Law of Peoples, p. 37.) It seems fair to say that Thomas Nagel’s revisions of Rawls’s theory in ‘The Problem of Global Justice’, Philosophy & Public A!airs, 33:2 (2005), pp. 113–48 also does not include a clear, ideal justification for the global authority. A similar puzzle arises in relation to the cosmopolitan theories of Charles Beitz, Thomas 2046 Helga Varden tell us what, exactly, is so wrong with the unilateral enforcement of global justice by an individual, a private security company, or a single state. Below I first argue that we can respect one another’s right to freedom only through the establishment of domestic public authorities (liberal states). Subsequently, I provide the comp- lementary account of why human rights and mutual respect for sovereignty among internally just states is possible only through the establishment of a global public authority. The need for domestic public authorities As indicated above, I believe that justice is possible only within civil society, or within a liberal, legal framework. Civil society is an enforceable precondition for right, and not merely a prudent response to the so-called ‘inconveniences’ characterising the state of nature. In my view, these conclusions follow if one accepts Kant’s relational understanding of right, according to which individuals’ interactions must be respectful of one another’s right to freedom. A right to freedom, on this view, is a right to set and pursue ends of one’s own choosing subject to universal laws of freedom rather than as subject to the arbitrary choices of another. Moreover, our interactions are rightful only if they are subject to restrictions of freedom, namely restrictions that are neither contingent, meaning that they are traceable to some particular person’s arbitrary judgement or preferences nor asymmetrical, meaning that they restrict people unequally. Such a right to freedom must be understood as innate, and since we are embodied beings, it must also be seen as involving a right to exist somewhere and to bodily integrity. That is to say, we must have a right to exist wherever we are born and we must have a right to defend our bodily integrity against attacks from others. Although the innate right to freedom gives one a right to protect oneself against attacks from others, it does not give us an individual right to punish. After all, rightful punishment requires determining non-contingent and symmetrical restrictions to be enforced against the perpetrator. Because it seems clear that there is reasonable disagreement with regard to issues of procedural justice and determinations of the amount of punishment, it is impossible for a private individual rightfully to enforce Pogge and Kok-Chor Tan. These cosmopolitan theories distinguish themselves from Rawls’s statism by using the wellbeing of individuals rather than societies (states or peoples) as the ultimate unit of analysis in considerations of global justice. Nevertheless, they do not make much headway with regard to settling the question of the status of the global authority. See, for example, Thomas Pogge, ‘An Egalitarian Law of Peoples’, Philosophy and Public A!airs, 23 (1994), pp. 195–224, and World Poverty and Human Rights (London: Polity Press, 2002), pp. 91–118 and 168–95. See also Kok-Chor Tan, Justice Without Borders: Cosmopolitanism, Nationalism and Patriotism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004); and Toleration, Diversity, and Global Justice (Pennsylvania: The Pennsylvania State University Press, 2000). For example, see Part III: ‘International Distributive Justice’, in Charles Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979), pp. 125–76; and ‘Human Rights and the Law of Peoples’, in Deen Chatterjee (ed.), The Ethics of Assistance: Morality and the Distant Needy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), pp. 193–216. Finally, despite his focus on international law and global institutions, Allen Buchanan also fails to address the ideal question of why we need public institutions in the first place. See his Justice, Legitimacy, and Self-Determination: Moral Foundations for International Law (New York: Oxford University Press, 2004). A Kantian conception of global justice 2047 her particular choice of procedures and punishment. Hence, rightful punishment requires the state: rightful punishment is impossible in the state of nature. Setting and pursuing ends of one’s own, however, requires more than a right to exist and to bodily integrity – and these further considerations yield other reasons why rightful interaction is impossible in the state of nature. More specifically, justice cannot be realised by each private individual acting virtuously, since private individuals can neither provide rightful assurance nor overcome certain problems of specification characterising private property, contract, and status (‘private care’) relations. The problem, in short, is that these relations among private individuals cannot be both rightful, and reconcilable with each person’s innate right to freedom, and determined and assured by a private authority. But private authority is the extent to which there is authority in the state of nature. Thus, though we may identify the general principles that should be governing the various areas of private interaction (private property, contract, and fiduciary relations), this identification is insu!cient for rightful relations. True, we can formulate the principles in a way that is reconcilable with each person’s innate right to freedom. But identifying these fundamental principles of rightful private interaction – or the principles of private right – is not enough to enable rightful relations. There is still a problem of providing assurance that we will so interact and of determining rightfully how these abstract principles should be specified in relation to various empirical circumstances and cases so that the resulting set of restrictions constrains each person’s actions symmetrically and non-contingently. Indeed, even a mutual agreement to trust one another and agreement on the specification of the principles cannot make relations among individuals rightful, since everyone’s freedom is still subject to one another’s arbitrary choice. Because it is in principle impossible for private individuals to solve the problems of assurance and specification of the principles of private right, refusing to enter civil society is to do wrong. In order to interact rightfully with others we must establish a condition in which our interactions are subject to universal laws of freedom rather than to one another’s arbitrary choices. The only way to do this is by establishing a will that represents the will of each and yet the will of no one particular private individual, that is, what Rousseau called a ‘general will’. I will call it a ‘public will’ or a ‘public authority’. To refuse to enter civil society is therefore to refuse the condition under which interaction consistent with each person’s right to freedom is possible – it is to ‘do wrong in the highest degree’, Kant argues. Thus, individuals have an enforceable duty to set up a public authority to provide assurance and to specify the rules for their interaction. They do not have a right to enforce their own specification even if it is a reasonable specification. Because consent cannot be a necessary condition for the establish- ment of a rightful state, we have good reason to think that the liberal ideal of political obligations at the state level is non-voluntarist in nature.5 5 Kant’s account of justice is found in the ‘Doctrine of Right’ in the Metaphysics of Morals. This text is found in Mary J. Gregor (trans. and ed.), Immanuel Kant: Practical Philosophy (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2006). I provide a fuller interpretation of Kant’s account of domestic private right in ‘Kant’s Non-Voluntarist Conception of Political Obligations: Why Justice is Impossible in the State of Nature’, Kantian Review, 13:2 (2008), pp. 1–45. 2048 Helga Varden The need for global public authorities Having seen how the Kantian conception of justice treats the domestic case, we can turn to the global case.6 First, it is important to note that the above argument establishes that a group of persons do nothing wrong by establishing a state. To the contrary, establishing a state is a precondition for rightful relations among interacting persons. Consequently, once there exists states, the coercive establish- ment of a world state with a global monopoly on coercion would be wrong because it would involve wrongfully depriving peoples of their rightfully established states. However we approach issues of global justice, our account can therefore not require a people to abolish their state, which means that the ideal of global justice cannot be the establishment of a world state with a global monopoly on coercion.7 Second, the just state is a public authority without private interests. Conse- quently, it does not have what we often refer to as ‘realist’ global interests, such as imperialist interests. If an actual liberal state has such interests, then it misunderstands or contradicts its own fundamental liberal principles. According to its own ideals, the just state’s domestic function is merely to enable rightful relations amongst its subjects. The corresponding global function is to pursue a condition in which it can interact rightfully with its neighbours and in which its citizens can interact rightfully with foreigners. Finally, note that on this relational conception of right, a state cannot rightfully use its citizens as means to solve other states’ or people’s problems. If you are not party to a particular conflict, then you do no wrong if you abstain from taking part in it. In other words, not only can 6 Kant’s main three writings on issues of global justice are ‘On the common saying: That may be correct in theory, but it is of no use in practice’ (PP), ‘Toward Perpetual Peace’ (TP), and the ‘Doctrine of Right’ in The Metaphysics of Morals (DR). The core challenge facing Kant interpreters concern dealing with the fact that he appears to be contradicting himself in his main texts on the issue. For example, there are some passages in each text, where Kant seems to argue that global justice is in principle impossible without a world state with a permanent monopoly on coercion (DR 6: 344, cf. 351, 354f; PP 8: 358, 379; TP 8: 310). Yet, in both PP and DR Kant appears to argue the contrary, namely that global justice cannot require a world state, but only requires a voluntary world republic (or ‘league of nations’). Kant appears to give several reasons – some principled and some pragmatic – why global justice cannot require a world state (DR 6: 344, 345f, 351); (PP 8: 354; 8: 355f). Further interpretive complexity is added by some passages where Kant seems to say that a world state is in theory necessary, but in practice it is impossible and, consequently, all we can establish is a voluntary world federation (DR 6: 350; PP 8: 367; TP 8: 310f) Finally, in PP, Kant famously argues that states, due to their mistaken understanding of the right of nations, will in practice (‘in hypothesi’) wrongly reject what is true in theory (‘in thesi’) (PP 8: 357, cf. 312). I engage Kant’s own text more carefully in ‘Diversity and Unity. An Attempt at Drawing a Justifiable Line’, Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie/Archives for Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy (ARSP), 94:1 (2008), pp. 1–25. 7 Until recently it commonly presupposed that according to Kant and the Kantian position, the public authority was needed simply because it constitutes the more e!cient means of ensuring peace. Consequently, whether a world state with a monopoly on coercion or a system of independent states was seen as an empirical question regarding which system is more likely to bring peace about. Michael W. Doyle, ‘Kant, Liberal Legacies, and Foreign A"airs 1/1’, Philosophy and Public A!airs, 11/12:3/4 (1983), pp. 205–35 and 323–53 and John Rawls (1999) famously pursue the statist line of argument. According to Doyle, liberal states have proven themselves less likely to go war against one another, and for both Doyle and Rawls, the aim is to identify which foreign policies liberal states should adopt in order to secure world peace. In contrast, Thomas Carson in ‘Perpetual Peace: what Kant Should Have Said’, Social Theory and Practice, 14:2 (1988), pp. 173–214; and Sidney Axinn in ‘World Community and Its Government’, in Jane Kneller and Sidney Axinn (eds), Autonomy and Community (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1998), pp. 119–29, argue that in our nuclear times, a world state with a monopoly on military power is more likely to secure world peace. A Kantian conception of global justice 2049 citizens never be rightfully forced to participate in expansionist wars, since states do not own their own citizens, but in addition citizens cannot be forced to participate in any conflicts to which they are not a party.8 Citizens can only be legally obliged to defend their own state against attacks. The implications of these preliminary remarks is that the pursuit of global justice for just states cannot involve the establishment of a world state with a global monopoly on coercion. Moreover, the level of required participation in the establishment of global institutions depends on the level and kind of interaction. So what are the kinds of global interaction? It seems that there are two kinds of interaction: interstate interaction and global private interaction. Clearly it is advantageous for an account of global justice if it can draw the proper distinctions between relations between states and relations that involve private individuals and yet are transnational in nature. The assumption that relations are only either statist or individual in nature fails to accurately capture the complexity of global interaction. This is a significant problem with statist and cosmopolitan theories. For example, Rawls’s statist account confines itself to an analysis of ideal relations simply in statist terms, and Tan’s account does the same only simply in individual terms. A virtue of the Kantian account is that it can distinguish between, and yet incorporate, both the right of nations (interstate interaction) and cosmopolitan right (transnational interaction involving private individuals).9 This in itself gives us some reason to pursue this third alternative, according to which accounts both of interactions involving states and of private persons are constituent parts of the full theory of global justice. So far I have argued that global justice cannot involve imperialism or the establishment of a world state with a permanent global monopoly on coercion and that the analysis should involve both analyses of interstate interaction and of private individual interaction. At this point it is fair to ask why we need any global public authority at all and also what it would look like if it is not a world state with a global monopoly on coercion? In answer to the first question, why, ideally, we need a global public authority at all, there are two reasons corresponding to the two relevant types of global interaction – between states and between states and foreign, private persons. Each type of interaction requires a public authority in order to be made rightful.10 8 See Kant in DR 6: 345f on this point. 9 In Kant’s DR the former account is found in ‘Public Right. Chapter II. The Right of Nations’ (6: 343–51), whereas the latter account is found in ‘Public Right. Chapter III. Cosmopolitan Right’ (6: 352–3). 10 Other non-prudential interpretations that deal with issues of global justice include Kevin E. Dodson, ‘Kant’s Perpetual Peace: Universal Civil Society or League of States’, Southwest Philosophical Studies, 15 (1993), pp. 1–9; Jürgen Habermas, ‘Kant’s Idea of Perpetual Peace, with the Benefit of Two Hundred Years’ Hindsight’, in James Bohman and Matthias Lutz-Bachmann (eds), Perpetual Peace: Essays on Kant’s Cosmopolitan Ideal (Cambridge, Massachusetts: the MIT Press, 1997), pp. 113–53; Otfried Hö"e, Kant’s Cosmopolitan Theory of Law and Peace, trans. Alexandra Newton (New York: Cambridge University Press), 2006; Pauline Kleingeld, ‘Approaching Perpetual Peace: Kant’s Defence of a League of States an his Ideal of a World Federation’, European Journal of Philosophy, 12:3 (2004), pp. 304–25; Nancy Kokaz, ‘Institutions for Global Justice’, in Daniel Weinstock (ed.), Global Justice, Global Institutions (Calgary: University of Calgary University Press, 2007); Thomas Pogge, ‘Kant’s Theory of Justice’, Kant-Studien, 79 (1988), pp. 407–33; Howard L. Williams, ‘Back from the USSR: Kant, Kalingrad and World Peace’, International Relations, 20:1 (2006), pp. 27–48. 2050 Helga Varden First, let me consider states’ interactions. There are two main types of ideal interaction among states: interaction in international spaces (in the air and on the sea) and interaction regarding borders. Even though individual states may specify the general principles to govern both interaction in international spaces and the determination of a proper border, there can be a reasonable disagreement about how to specify them. And though it is advantageous if various states can work things out, say through a willingness to engage in a Habermasian discourse or a Rawlsian political discourse, there can still be reasonable disagreement regarding exactly where the actual lines should be drawn. Although it is often unreasona- bleness that leads to conflict, disagreements can also be reasonable. The only way to find a solution to such a deadlock that is consistent with a commitment to a liberal ideal of rightful freedom involves establishing a public authority to decide the matter. Just as in the domestic case only a public authority can represent both parties to the conflict and yet no one in particular. Therefore, a rightful solution to problems involving interactions between states in international spaces requires the establishment of such an authority. Since states can reasonably disagree, it seems that a true commitment to rightful peace involves a willingness to establish an international authority with standing to specify and apply the laws governing these kinds of interactions. States committed to rightful peace will, insofar as possible, coercively defend only borders so determined. Only coercion authorised by the global authority in this way is reconcilable with rightful peace. It is for these kinds of reasons that liberal states want something like the International Court of Justice (ICJ).11 Second, there are interactions between states and foreign private individuals. Ideally, there are only voluntary visitors to a state.12 Voluntary visitors are persons 11 This is an argument that is particularly important for countries with contested borders, such as Norway. Norway is involved in many of the controversial international disputes concerning borders on Svalbard, the Arctic and o"shore borders in the North Atlantic Ocean, and the Barents Sea. Norway typically follows the relevant rulings of the International Court of Justice in these matters, and yet a lot of the theoretical and public o!cials’ analyses of these matters are undertaken in realist and increasingly neoliberal terms. A drawback of these analyses is that they only partially grasp why Norway find it so important to look to the international authority when formulating its own national policies, including its foreign policies, regarding these matters. The partial reason stems from prudence – as a small nation, Norway has no option but to work with other political forces when pursuing its interests. The argument presented here is not antithetical to or incompatible with prudential reasons, but it maintains that the commitment to the ICJ can also be seen as a consequence of Norway’s general commitment to function as a liberal legal system. Which reason is actually operating depends on the extent to which Norway is able to function as a public authority, of course. But the main point here is that liberal institutional commitments to right are fundamentally incompatible with unilateralism and consequently insofar as liberal states progress, they will be increasingly resistant to use unilateralism in their global interactions. 12 Involuntary visitors are refugees. States can justify their territorial monopoly on coercion only if it is consistent with everyone’s innate right to freedom. Hence, though a state need not give permission to everyone wanting to enter its territory, it cannot turn away those who have nowhere safe to go. If it does, then the state’s use of coercion is irreconcilable with its own foundation, since such exclusion is irreconcilable with the refugee’s innate right to freedom – it would not be reconcilable with everyone’s right to exist somewhere. Moreover, even as the state lets the refugee across its border, there arises the problem that until the refugee has obtained legal status as a citizen, the particular state in which she is living is not her public authority. The state in representing the general will of the people does not thereby represent her will. Therefore, until citizenship is conferred, the state does not fully representing the refugee. On this account, it is in recognition of these kinds of problems of reconciling a state’s monopoly on coercion with a visitor’s innate right to freedom that current states have instituted the UNHCR (The O!ce of the UN High Commissioner for Refugees: {http://www.unhcr.org/basics.html}. This global public institution represents both states and refugees, A Kantian conception of global justice 2051 who visit (tourists) or live over longer periods in a di"erent country not out of need, but because they would like to pursue a professional or private interest in this way. They do not have a right to enter another state, but if they are permitted to enter, the challenge for the state concerns how to enable rightful interactions between itself, its citizens and the foreigners. The first response from just states is to guarantee the visitors legal protection by giving them various types of legal residence status, such as tourist visas, temporary work visas, permanent residence, and so on. As long as a person is not a citizen, she or he does not enjoy full citizen rights, but many of these rights in virtue of being granted these kinds of legal status. Moreover, as mentioned above, private individuals do not have a right to punish; only the state can. Yet since the state does not fully represent the visitors (the resident does not have full rights), the next challenge for the just states concerns how they can still rightfully punish the visitors? We see just states responding to this problem in a variety of ways. For example, just states provide legal aid to the foreigner, secure foreign embassies the rights to assist their citizens (the resident), or negotiate extradition treaties. The suggestion in this article is that it is because the state does not fully represent the foreigners that they try to secure their rights by involving the state, of which the foreigner is a citizen, in these ways.13 Finally, there are transnational issues concerning private property, trade, and fiduciary relations. Private persons inherit property in other states, engage in international trade, and marry and have children across state borders. There are therefore private right cases involving private property, contracts, and fiduciary relations where at least one party to the conflict is located in a di"erent state then the other(s). Again, the challenge for the state is how to make these interactions rightful and the main problem concerns which laws the state should apply in any particular transnational case at hand. For example, it can be a US airline company filing a case in the US legal system suing a Belgian airline company for an accident involving several American airplanes at the Brussels airport, or it can be a Canadian couple adopting a child from Korea, and then the Korean biological parents challenge the rightfulness of the adoption in the Korean legal system. In these kinds of cases, there is a so-called ‘conflict of laws’, which means that it is unclear which domestic laws should be applied in the particular case: should it be and it is the means through which states and refugee interaction are made rightful. In addition, of course, the UNHCR deals with other non-ideal situations, such as by trying to set up safe places for refugees, by regulating any other non-state interaction with refugees, and by facilitating their transition to permanent new homes in new states. Finally, it follows that the public authority will seek to maintain a global peacekeeping force as required to stabilise and assist currently stateless peoples as they (re)build their just states. No state’s military can fulfil such a role (ideally), since it cannot (in principle) act on behalf of the stateless people; only a global public authority can. Moreover, because the public authority cannot command anyone to risk their lives in such peacekeeping missions, the UN must maintain its peacekeeping force purely by voluntary means. 13 The International Criminal Court’s (ICC) {http://www.icc-cpi.int/}, in contrast, is a means of securing just punishment on behalf of defenceless persons and peoples – or persons and peoples who, in e"ect, are stateless and hence deprived of protection by a just state. It is therefore a non-ideal measure in that it enables rightful punishment of aggressive, violent behaviour that otherwise cannot be punished (since one of the parties exists in the state of nature). It should therefore, if things go well, be incorporated into the UN structure proper. This seems consistent with how the founding document of the ICC makes it clear that even though the ICC is currently independent of the UN (Article 2, ‘Rome Statue of the International Criminal Court’, downloaded from ICC’s homepage on 17 Feb. 2010), ‘The Court shall be brought into relationship with the UN through an agreement to be approved by the Assembly of States Parties to this Statute . . .’. 2052 Helga Varden the laws of the legal system where the suit is filed or the laws of the legal system of the defendant? In order to deal with these problems, many states have developed so-called ‘international private right’, which are laws aimed at deciding how legal systems should deal with these kinds of conflicts. Moreover, in the last few decades, individual states have been trying to coordinate their international private right systems, especially through the Hague Conference on Private International Law (HCCH). In my view, this is the first step towards making such interactions rightful, namely by establishing which principles should determine which states’ laws should be relevant in various types of cases. The further step seems to involve establishing an international court with standing to evaluate whether or not states properly applied the principles of international private right. Since a particular state is not the public authority of all the interacting parties, a global authority as an ultimate appeal is necessary for rightful relations involving international private right. Hence, though the HCCH is a step in the right direction, it is not the last step if things go well. The institutional structure of public authorities Having argued that we need both domestic and transnational public authorities, we need to obtain a clearer idea of what such public authorities look like.14 In particular, we want to make sure that establishing these authorities does not merely reproduce the problems of the state of nature by subjecting freedom to someone’s arbitrary choice rather than to non-contingent and symmetrical law. This requires us to identify the institutional structure of the public authorities. Again, let’s take a look at the domestic case before turning to the global case. The institutional structure of domestic public authorities To avoid the problematic conditions of the state of nature, first, the state cannot have ‘private’ interests; second, it must guarantee all its citizens’ freedom and 14 I believe the charitable reading of Georg Cavallar, Kant and the Theory and Practice of International Right (Cardi": University of Wales Press, 1999); Dobson (1993), Habermas (1997), Hö"e (2006), Kleingeld (2004), Kokaz (2007), Maus (2006), and Pogge (1988, 2009) agree with me that according to Kant rightful solutions to conflicts in interstate relations and in relations between states and foreigners require the institution of a global public authority. The main di"erences are as follows: Dobson and Hö"e argue that Kant’s ideal reasons for not establishing a global authority with a monopoly on coercion should be rejected and instead our aim for the global authority should be what Hö"e calls a ‘minimal state’. Habermas and Pogge, in contrast, argue that the considered Kantian position defends an overlap between domestic, regional, and global spheres of sovereignty. Maus uses the point to support her view that global justice requires that just states always remain independent of one another, even though they ought to use global institutions like the Court of Justice to settle their disputes. Cavallar, Kokaz and Kleingeld, in turn, use these ideal arguments for the necessity of the global authority as providing further support for their developmental conceptions of the world federation with some limited coercive powers. In contrast I have argued that the global public authority is the only rightful authoriser of coercion regarding interstate relations (though the individual just states do the actual enforcing) and that the global peacekeeping force is limited to the protection of stateless individuals. Finally, I have argued that the choice to partake in other states’ and stateless peoples’ conflicts is a choice that ultimately lies with each state’s individuals. A Kantian conception of global justice 2053 equality by both securing for each one of them rights to bodily integrity and to private right, and by setting itself up as a tripartite coercive authority that specifies, applies, and enforces only the law. Thus, to overcome the problems of the state of nature and to establish a condition in which rightful relations are possible, the public authority requires a constitution or a similar fundamental legal document circumscribing its fundamental powers in these ways. These circumscriptions make it possible for the public authority to be authorised to act on behalf of its people in order to enable their rightful interaction – interaction that was impossible in the state of nature. The public authority cannot own private property or have any private interests because this would make it impossible to represent no one in particular, and yet all its citizens. The public authority treats them as free and equal by securing their rights to bodily integrity and private rights and by establishing the sovereign as the rule of public law so that the law rules the o!ces of the sovereign authority. In addition to setting the sovereign power up in these ways designed to overcome the problems of the state of nature, the state must take certain additional steps to secure conditions of justice because it must establish a monopoly on coercion. That is to say, because the state must assume a monopoly on coercion, it must also ensure that monopoly on coercion is reconcilable with everyone’s right to freedom, namely their right not to find their freedom subject to another private person’s arbitrary choice, but only to the public authority’s laws. This is why the state must provide unconditional poverty relief, why it must assume special control over land, the economy and financial systems, and why it must set up a public administration and a system of punishment. Each of these systemic measures is necessary to ensure that citizens do not find their freedom, although determined by institutions, e"ectively under the control of some private person. Establishing such public institutions with the appropriate structure is a matter of public right, namely it concerns the claims citizens subjects have on their public institutions in virtue of their citizenship. Therefore, public rights are not coextensive with the rights people have against one another as private persons. Rather the claims of domestic public right are di"erent in nature and kind by being systemic claims citizens have only with regard to their own state.15 The institutional structure of the global public authority Let’s now return to the global case. How, exactly, do we set up a global public authority, which is to say how do we reform the UN? As in the domestic case, I believe that there are three main institutional processes that must take place. First, the establishment of a global public authority requires a founding legal document circumscribing its authority in ways similar to the domestic case. Second, this document must specify the public global authority and the way in which it is comprised of three independent yet complementary public institutions: a legislative authority, a judicial authority, and an executive authority. Third, consistent with 15 I provide an interpretation of this public right argument to Kant’s ‘Doctrine of Right’ in ‘Kant’s Non-Absolutist Conception of Political Legitimacy: How Public Right “Concludes” Private Right in ‘The Doctrine of Right’’, Kant-Studien (forthcoming). 2054 Helga Varden the legal foundation, other public institutions must be established to enable and secure systemic justice. The current UN, albeit in need of significant reform to secure global justice, is at least approaching minimally meeting all three conditions in a way that is reconcilable with just states’ sovereignty. Because of some unjustifiable asymmetries that characterise the UN’s core institutions, some improvements seem pertinent to their ability to issue political obligations on interacting states in all regards, but there seems to have been clear institutional improvement over its short history. Consequently, although there may still be some time before these institutions are capable of functioning as public authorities capable of issuing political obligations, I do not see that there are any principled reasons why we shouldn’t be able to reform them so as to overcome these problems. To start, the ideal function of the UN Charter is to serve as the founding legal document for international public right, and therefore it is the document within which all the other UN institutions must act. Moreover, it specifies the tripartite structure of the public authority required for international right. The legislative authority currently lies with the General Assembly, and the judicial authority is currently identified with the International Court of Justice. And consistent with what I have argued, if things progress rather than regress, a suitably constructed analogue to the Hague Conference on Private International Law will also become parts of the UN judicial authority. Central to further progress regarding all institutions, I believe, focuses on being able to reform them into institutional authorities that reason and act as public authorities – namely as authorities representing all and yet no one in particular. This naturally includes progress with regard to establishing the principles determining which judges are necessarily biased in which types of cases. The more we are able to do this, the more unreasonable and irrational it becomes to insist on settling transnational conflicts by unilateral means. The executive authority primarily lies with the Security Council, which is authorised to decide when member states can be called upon to intervene in situations where international rightful peace and security is threatened. Since the Security Council must be reconcilable with just states’ sovereignty, not only must the just states’ own citizens have the last word on intervention, it will only authorise coercion aimed at stopping international violence or domestic violence within unjust states. The enforcement of the authoritative decisions made by the UN is carried out by the just states themselves and/or by the UN Peacekeeping forces. Moreover, it seems fair to say that the main challenge with regard to this authority concerns reforming the Security Council into an authority that can be seen as representing all its legal subjects – all just states – as free and equal. Today’s system of veto by permanent members and the possible election of the most unjust states as members of the Security Council may be prudent given the global climate, but I cannot see that it can fulfil its function as a public authority until it becomes based on a firm commitment to freedom and equality. What about the third condition, namely of securing systemic justice? Interest- ingly, the General Assembly, the ICJ, and the Security Council comprise only three of the six original bodies established by the UN Charter. The other three are the Economic and Social Council, the Trusteeship Council, and the Secretariat. Without looking at the details surrounding these institutions, it is fair to say that A Kantian conception of global justice 2055 they all concern systemic issues related to global interaction – that is, systemic issues related to the global economy, including poverty, peoples without indepen- dence as a result of historic imperialism, and public administration. All of these issues were identified by the founders of the UN as central to establishing a global system of public right. Moreover, as time has passed, other institutions have been added, far too many to mention here. Rather, what is important is that there seems to be a fairly clear structure to the growth of the UN as an institutional whole. It is similar to how the public institutions of just states have and still do increase in number or grow to enable conditions of rightful interaction for all its citizens. New institutions, whether on the domestic or global front, are necessary to fill out the public institutional structure required for rightful relations (rightful peace) for all. Since on the global front we need a fairly comprehensive system to deal with international spaces, international private right and systemic right, we are now seeing the growth of institutions in all these areas. On the one hand, we see an increasing number of public or quasi-public institutions aimed at enabling borders and international private right. As already mentioned, in addition to the ICJ for border and international space issues, we have the O!ce of the UN High Commissioner for Refugees (UNHCR) specialising in refugee issues. In addition, there are increasing numbers of institutions aimed at enabling international private right, such as the World Trade Organization (WTO) and the quasi-public HCCH, which, I suggest, will be reformed into a public authority if things go well. On the other hand, we have an increasing number of institutions aimed at enabling systemic justice with respect to the global economy and the international financial system. This explains some of the complexity of the World Trade Organization’s operations as well as institutions like the World Intellectual Property Organization (WIPO). We also have institutions aiming to make it possible for states to have interacting economies and financial systems without thereby risking the downfall of these states. To that end, the UN has set up the International Monetary Fund (IMF), the World Bank (WB), and the World Health Organization (WHO). Like the original Economic and Social Council called for under the UN Charter, their primary function is to help the stabilisation and growth of international global systems without also creating, even unintentionally, destructive dependency relations between states. This is not to say that there are some serious asymmetries involved in the current institutions, such as the way in which the Western countries control the WTO, the IMF and the World Bank. Rather the main point is that current UN already includes much of the necessary structural features to serve as a just global public authority. Therefore, although all these institutions still require significant reform, the current UN charter establishes a coherent institutional structure that can be reformed into the kind of public authority necessary to enable global justice. Conclusion Despite my conditionals in the arguments above, the main objection to my conclusions is still likely to be that many of these UN institutions are notoriously corrupt and unjust deserving only of the rubbish heap, so let’s just scrap them and 2056 Helga Varden start from square one. Let me therefore just emphasise again that I completely agree that the current UN institutions are corrupt and unjust. But I also believe that the above account says something about what makes such institutions corrupt and explains why the solution to our current problems requires us to fix these institutions from within. On the one hand, these institutions are unjust because they do not treat all their legal subjects (states and persons) as free and equal. There are certain institutional asymmetries that simply must be overcome before they can properly issue political obligations. But because proper institution building takes time, this will take time. On the other hand, the alternative to fixing global public institutions seems to be to settle for unilateralism of powerful states, which is worse. It is worse because it is the incarnation of the asymmetry problem currently characterising aspects of the UN institutions. Of course, unilateralism that involves enforcing illiberal principles is worse than unilateralism that involves enforcing liberal principles. But that is not the point here. Since I’m after identifying the liberal ideal to strive for, the main point is that all unilateralism necessarily involves interaction between states as unequals subject to contingent and asymmetrical restrictions. Unilateral- ism cannot in principle enable global justice. After all, even an internally just, powerful state cannot rightfully enable global justice because it cannot in principle be impartial, have rightful standing in particular transnational disputes or assume rightful authority over global systems of interaction. The reason is simply that any particular state can only represent the general united will of its own people. Therefore, it cannot in principle have the rightful authority to specify, apply or enforce private or public right beyond its own territory since it does not represent the world as such. Indeed, even the state’s own, reasonably contested borders are beyond its own rightful authority. Because siding with unilateralism cannot in principle lead to rightful relations, the only way forward with regard to establishing global justice requires reforming the UN by working towards eliminating the institutional asymmetries that currently exist. And as they are eliminated, liberal states can and must increase their institutional commitment to them too. Finally, since the UN has much of the required institutional framework in place, also the prudent way seems to be to reform it rather than start all over again. After all, just as with states, there is no good reason to think that starting all over again is going to be much easier and get us much further, faster, than reform will. A Kantian conception of global justice 2057 work_jq3bmf6libh5da2e4hkrnusw7u ---- Environmental justice: partnerships for communication. NIEHS News- Middle East Agricultural Health Study An agreement to study the human health effects of pesticides in the Middle East enthusiastically adopted by foreignR 3 ters and other officials from sevet4 East countries, the West Bank,, the European Community, the United States. TheM s" Agricultural Health Study,cbev y the NIEHS and the Fogarty International Center at the National Institutes of Health, was approved at a meeting in Manama, Bahrain, in October 1994. The next step took place in December, when technical experts from the Middle East and North America met at a workshop in Cairo to iron out the details of the NIH initiative. The Agricultural Health Study is part of the broader Middle East Peace Initiative. While the meeting of foreign ministers in Bahrain set the NIH proposal in motion, the regional workshop in Egypt addressed logistical issues related to gathering data, current collaborations on pesticide use, and implementing the study. Scientific experts from academic insti- tutions and government agencies from the Middle East region expressed concern frustration that dramatic environment impacts of population changes and agrc tural, technological, and industrial ad- vances in the region have not been ade- quately studied and are often unrecognized by government officials and the general public. Participants proposed collaborative research, communication, and education strategies to address these environmental concerns. Studies on the health effects of agricultural chemicals were identified as a top priority. Agricultural chemicals are usually mix- tures of chemicals, some of which can damage the environment and accumulate in ecosystems, including ground- and sur- face water, and contaminate the food sup- ply. Many agricultural chemicals can cause a range of adverse human health effects. Children may be particularly vulnerable. The NIH proposal attempts to better de- fine the extent of adverse health effects in the Middle East region, promote the safe use of pesticides, and ensure the applica- tions of the most effective pesticide-man- agement guidelines. In densely populated areas, large quan- tities of pesticides are used annually. In addition to pesticides, fertilizers, growth regulators, food additives, synthetic dyes, detergents, and dusts are sources of pollu- tion in the environment. There is an urgent need to health ts reand e chanisms of to e major compo 1 is a research .,ncer conse c8tittf | | exposure f populations. Potential collaborators for these health effects studies have been iden- tified in Egypt, Israel, Jordan, the West Bank and the Gaza Strip, and the United States. Scientists from other nations in the region will also be invited to particia. The experimental plan will address neurological deficits, childhood develop- ment, birth defects, od hypertension as health endpoints tc measurements will assess ner*"4" velocity, ace- tylcholinest vuci, ale- assessmet, hearing, bloo and gross po f the is the Peace E ships designedi rjunior- frot cipating Uni to gain experi- rch that will be used irho S. The training ini- IV a cadre of young ea s dedicated to environ- me o ccupational health in estab- lish torships and enhance the work- ing retionship among scientists in the United States and the Middle East. The proposed collaborative studies among scientists within the region will allow new intervention and prevention approaches to better manage the risks of agricultural chemical use. Furthermore, communication and health education strategies involving the NIH proposal will assist national policymakers and local cow, ens of he * Communities n n, d *Assessment ofAviable Dat * Training Peace Felos * Humn Health Effcs Reseac authorities in devising mitigation plans on the use of agricultural chemicals. ental Justice: ips for ation ng the goals of the NIEHS f search aimed at achieving F P If+~htajustice for all populations. Assays of the health effects of environmen- tal pollution, as well as regulations based on such assays, are often performed with little or no input from affected communi- ties. The purpose of the communication program is to institute mechanisms to brie this communication gap so that the communities involved have a role in iden- tifyng and defining problems and risks related to environmental health and in shaping future research approaches to such problems. A Request for Applications was initially issued in January 1994. Applications were evaluated by a Special Review Committee composed of environmental health researchers, health care providers, and community representatives. Three awards, two of which address Native American issues, were made in September 1994. Environmental investigators at Clark University, in collaboration with Native Americans for a Clean Environment and Citizen Alert Native American Program, are seeking to increase the awareness of Native American communities exposed to radiation contamination. These communi- ties bear a disproportionate burden of risk from nuclear activities, ranging from urani- um mining to waste disposal. Members of the affected communities are ill prepared to understand and deal with the hazards of radiation contamination. The grantee will design and implement a plan for risk man- agement and prevention activities at the Western Shoshone Nation near the Nevada Test Site and at the Cherokee Nation at Sequoyah Fuels, Oklahoma, a uranium processing facility in operation for 23 years. Education modules of two types will be implemented: community modules, created exclusively by Native American collaborators; and health educa- tion modules, created by scientists and health care provider trainers. Each of these components involves the community in learning about health risks and in sharing their perspectives of this risk with scientists and health professionals. Relevant materi- als and strategies will be shared with other Native American communities. 22 Environmental Health Perspectives 9- The State University of New York, Albany, in collaboration with St. Regis Mohawk Health Services, intends to design community-based strategies for environmental health education, outreach, and training in the Akwesasne Mohawk community, which is adjacent to a Super- fund site in the Great Lakes Basin-St. Lawrence River watershed. Environmental hazards have resulted from the rapid tran- sition from an agricultural to an industrial environment. Industry appears to have produced high levels of polychlorinated biphenyls (PCBs) from manufacture of hydraulic fluids until 1973. Sludge con- taining PCBs was placed in disposal pits adjacent to the Akwesasne community and has been found in water and soil in the area. Sediments have been found in the St. Lawrence River, which serves as a major source of fish, a protein staple in the Mohawk diet. Contaminants have been found in human breast milk, and a num- ber of symptom-related health effects have been experienced by residents. Chronic fluoride poisoning has been observed in cattle, resulting from smokestacks emis- sions of a metal smelter. Lethal levels of organochlorines have been found in tissues of some animals in the immediate environ- ment. This project is led and directed by members of the target community. It is implemented, evaluated, and disseminated explicitly through community members. The project team has worked together extensively and has nine years of experi- ence in communicating information on health risks to the community. A third grant funded under this initia- tive was awarded to a community organi- zation, Citizens for a Better Environment. This group, in collaboration with the Labor Occupational Safety and Health Program and the Center for Occupational and Environmental Health at UCLA and the Community Health Foundation, aims to educate community members and health care providers, promote adoption of pollution prevention measures, and estab- lish a community-based strategy for reduc- ing community and worker exposure to environmental pollutants in southeast Los Angeles, a highly industrialized area home to a low-income population, approximate- ly 90% Hispanic/Latino. Pollution sources include large, highly industrialized tracts where chemicals are routinely or acciden- tally released, severe urban smog, occupa- tional exposures, and lead exposures. The zip code area which includes southeast Los Angeles was identified as the dirtiest subre- gion within the state of California by the EPA. About 70 manufacturing firms in South East Los Angeles reported releases of 1.4 million pounds of toxic chemicals into the air in 1992. A major objective of this project is analysis of data to affirm the list of environmental pollutants already known and to determine whether gaps exist in the data. Environmental health issues of prior- ity to the community will be determined and addressed. CBE has already received invitations from mayors and council mem- bers to help reduce community toxics exposure. CBE helped to develop LA CAUSE (Los Angeles Communities Assembled and United for a Sustainable Environment), a community education project that seeks to promote environmen- tally friendly jobs. LA CAUSE will involve and educate community members and has a history of reaching residents and workers from the region. Sources of health hazards will be identified, and strategies will be developed to attempt exposure reduction. Book Addresses Parents' Concerns about Toxins I "Everything causes cancer," according to the old cliche. Now parents, pediatricians, social workers, and oth- ers concerned about children's health have a concise guide, Raising Children Toxic Free, to help them identify the real toxic hazards and adopt practical, simple precautions to protect chil- dren and themselves. The book covers toxins that impact reproduction, behavior, development, envi- ronmental neurotoxins, and cancer. Agents discussed specifically include lead, mercury, asbestos, pesticides, radiation, tobacco, solvents and PCBs, and air pollution. The book was written by Herbert L. Needleman, profes- sor of psychiatry and pediatrics at the University of Pittsburgh School of Medicine, and Philip J. Landrigan, profes- sor of pediatrics and chair of community medicine and director of the NIEHS Environmental Health Sciences Center at Mount Sinai School of Medicine in New York City. The publisher is Farrar, Straus and Giroux, New York. While some of the remedies suggested require community and political action (asbestos in the schools), other remedial action is quite direct. For example, parents can air clothes just back from the dryclean- ers outdoors to reduce exposure to per- chloroethylene fumes in the home. Avoiding fruits and vegetables imported from outside the United States, where pes- ticides may not be properly used, is anoth- er simple step. NIEHS Awards Grants for EMF Research NIEHS and the Department of Energy are coordinating the implementation of the 1992 Energy Policy Act (Section 2118 of Public Law 102-486), which was signed in October 1992. This is a five-year federally coordinated effort to evaluate developing technologies and research related to the effects on biological systems of exposure to electric and magnetic fields produced by the generation, transmission, and use of electric energy. The Department of Energy is responsi- ble for developing technologies to charac- terize and mitigate these fields, while NIEHS is responsible for coordinating and conduct- ing studies to evaluate the possible adverse health effects related to exposures to these fields and for communicating of these findings to policymakers and the public. The NIEHS has a long history of funding research in this area. In August 1994, the National Toxicology Program began two- year rodent studies of the effects of mag- netic fields. Magnetic fields, rather than electric, are being evaluated because epidemiological studies are most consistent for an association of cancer with magnetic fields. New grants administered through the NIEHS Division of Extramural Research and Training, funded by the Energy Policy Act of 1992 (Section 2118 of Public Law 102-486) have further broadened NIEHS research on electromagnetic fields. Newly awarded grants funded by the Energy Policy act are: * Dean Astumian, University of Chicago: Interactions between low-frequency AC electric fields and yeast membrane pro- teins; * Elizabeth Balcer-Kubiczek, University of Maryland, Baltimore: Effects of 60 Hz EMFs on the expression of genes associ- ated with cancer in human cell lines, HL-60 and MCF-7; * David Binninger, Florida Atlantic University, Boca Raton: Molecular basis for the effects of 60 Hz EMFs on gene expression (transcription) in yeast; * Craig Byus, University of California, Volume 103, Number 1, January 1995 23 work_jqihww2udbgrfc6has3s425t7y ---- Microsoft Word - 116 Rizza, et al. Do-it-yourself justice: the 2011 Vancouver Riots Proceedings of the 10 th International ISCRAM Conference – Baden-Baden, Germany, May 2013 T. Comes, F. Fiedrich, S. Fortier, J. Geldermann and T. Müller, eds. 411 “Do-it-yourself justice”: considerations of social media use in a crisis situation: the case of the 2011 Vancouver riots Caroline Rizza European Commission, JRC – Telecom ParisTech caroline.rizza@telecom-paristech.fr Ângela Guimarães Pereira European Commission, JRC angela.pereira@jrc.ec.europa.eu Paula Curvelo European Commission, JRC paula.curvelo@jrc.ec.europa.eu ABSTRACT On 15 June 2011, the ice hockey Stanley Cup final series between the Vancouver Canucks and the Boston Bruins took place in Vancouver. As the Vancouver Canucks were losing, riots started in downtown Vancouver. Social media were used to communicate between authorities and citizens, including the rioters. The media reporting on these events frame these communications with different narratives, which in turn raise different ethical considerations. This paper identifies those narratives and reflects upon the ideas of justice, fairness, responsibility, accountability and integrity as key ethical considerations. The paper also identifies some difficulties arising from the use of social media in crisis situations. Keywords Crisis situations; social media, ethics; media narratives. INTRODUCTION On 15 June 2011, the ice hockey Stanley Cup final took place between the Vancouver Canucks and the Boston Bruins in Vancouver, Canada. Riots started downtown as the Vancouver Canucks were losing the final. The riots lasted all night long (Furlong and Keefe 2011). At the same time and following the event, different people (mainly rioters, local authority officers, and Vancouver citizens) used social media to ‘cover’ the riots: the rioters took pictures and video of themselves and uploaded them; local authorities used social media to communicate with fellow citizens 1 and Vancouver citizens to help local authorities identify rioters 2 , by sharing and tagging pictures of rioters and, last but not least, to enforce justice by themselves 3 . The use of social media during the riots has raised issues such as the quality of legal processes in which such media are used to provide evidence, mob behaviour, or vigilante justice. In this paper we look at the story from the point of view of the news media narratives, i.e. what the media coverage echoed and commented on at the time of the riots, to gain an insight into the imaginaries behind the use of social media such as Facebook and Twitter. In particular, we will be looking at narratives about social media and ethical considerations as portrayed by the news media. 1 See the VPD website: https://riot2011.vpd.ca/ [last visit 11/02/2013]. 2 See e.g. https://www.facebook.com/vancouverriot2011photos?sk=photos; http://www.identifyrioters.com/?photo=64; or http://www.techi.com/2011/06/social-media-used-to-identify- vancouver-riot-suspects/ [last visit 11/02/2013]. 3 See the VPD website: http://vpdreleases.icontext.com/2011/06/20/vpd-statement/ [last visit 11/02/2013]. Rizza, et al. Do-it-yourself justice: the 2011 Vancouver Riots Proceedings of the 10 th International ISCRAM Conference – Baden-Baden, Germany, May 2013 T. Comes, F. Fiedrich, S. Fortier, J. Geldermann and T. Müller, eds. 412 STATE OF THE ART The study of crowd dynamics has been in the literature for some decades (Gorringe, & Rosie, 2011). The authors provide a chronology of contemporary understanding of crowd behaviour. The representation of crowds as an irrational, senseless herd was challenged in the 1960s. At that time, crowds were seen as an attempt to short-circuit the political system and police intervention was considered the key solution to restore order in riot situations. The rational and interactive nature of collective behaviour was not given much consideration until later (Gorringe & Rosie, 2011). In the case of Vancouver 2011, the ‘crowd effect’ played an important role during the riots, but also after the riots, as citizens became involved in law enforcement activities in response to the Vancouver Police Department (VPD)’s asking them to send pictures and videos or identify the rioters. In a crisis situation, the involvement of citizens in developing emergency response and relief plans for their immediate community is not new (Heverin, 2011). More specifically, in a violent crisis situation, citizens may collectively respond with a strong sense of justice, by demanding the arrest and punishment of the perpetrators (Heverin, 2011). However, in comparison to other cases of citizen involvement, the collective involvement of citizens in law enforcement activities – whether this is spontaneous or inspired by explicit requests such as the VPD’s – creates a greater risk of abuse and unexpected severe consequences. Heverin (2011)underlines that this risk increases exponentially with the use of social media, which “increase the visibility of participation, allow for instantaneous dissemination of information about police and perpetrators to a wide audience”. This is what happened after the Vancouver riots. This spontaneous way of capturing data in a crisis situation is also called “crowd-sourced surveillance” (Samuel, 2011). The author believes that this kind of surveillance is not without dangers: whatever the goodwill at the beginning of the public disclosure of information about the rioters, it has been belied by an increasingly violent tone; even if analysts and internet users condemn the Vancouverite social media responses as those of a “cruel, faceless, vindictive mob”, this does not take away from general awareness of how social media such as Facebook have been used and could be used to target any particular group; the Vancouver model of crowd-sourced law enforcement could be adopted in repressive jurisdictions or circumstances. Social media could be, and have already been, used by law enforcement officers to identify criminals. In this context, the ethical considerations with regard to this use of social media should focus on the legitimacy of such material (pictures, videos) and its use in identifying perpetrators and pressing charges. But automated or crowd-sourced identification could also be used by repressive law enforcement systems. This is a major cause of concern from the point of view of human rights. Another ethical consideration arises when citizens themselves initiate and participate in the crowd-sourced identification of others using social media, even if they are asked to do so by law enforcement officers. Crowd-sourced surveillance by citizens cannot be fully controlled by law enforcement officers, as was the case during the Vancouver riots. In the literature, a crisis situation has been defined by reference to the degree of emergency that overrides a normal democratic process in decision-making (Mullins, 2005). In such a situation, decision-makers are likely to have to make complex ethical judgments under great uncertainty, time pressure, and heightened public scrutiny (Svedin, 2011). Public trust in governing institutions depends greatly on the way decision-makers deal with the ethical dilemmas and normative challenges that arise in a crisis. Most of these dilemmas come to the fore in circumstances where a number of fundamental ethical values are threatened in the light of modern legislation on human rights. The essence of a crisis lies in this threat to fundamental values. A crisis situation is characterised by the presence of value conflicts, doubts about the legitimacy of intervention, contradictory views regarding the private and public spheres, disruption of democratic processes, inadequate communication and participation, to mention but a few aspects (Svedin, 2011). In Western tradition, ethical principles are based on values that are the result of millennia of religious and humanistic study and practice, and are recognised by those who share the heritage of a democratic society (Zack, 2009). In a crisis situation, how good or bad the circumstances are, is determined by expectations: “bad circumstances are not an excuse for bad ethics” (Zack, 2009). The consequences of various alternative solutions can in some cases be quantified, using theories of risk assessment by trying to answer the following three questions: “What can go wrong?”, “How likely is it to happen?”, and “What are the consequences?” (Budinger, & Budinger, 2006). On this basis, there is little doubt that the Vancouver riots constituted a crisis situation during which local decision-makers (the Mayor, VPD officers, etc.) were obliged to make decisions quickly to protect the city, its citizens and their property from rioters. The call for volunteers to send pictures and videos and identify rioters online can be considered part of these decisions. The way citizens began to enforce vigilante justice, what we will call “do it yourself justice”, even before the VPD asked them to do so, infringed ethical values, even if at the time it appeared to them to be the right course of action. Responsibility therefore lies with local authorities. METHODOLOGY AND RESULTS Our aim is to examine the news media narratives around the time of the riots, i.e. what the media echoed and Rizza, et al. Do-it-yourself justice: the 2011 Vancouver Riots Proceedings of the 10 th International ISCRAM Conference – Baden-Baden, Germany, May 2013 T. Comes, F. Fiedrich, S. Fortier, J. Geldermann and T. Müller, eds. 413 commented on, in relation to ethics and social networks. We agree with the statement that “the construction of news is most of all a reconstruction of available discourses” (van Dick, 1983). The riots received a lot of coverage in the Canadian news media. They also grabbed the attention of bloggers, and the reactions they provoked in the media and among the public show that the use of social networks raises awareness of how some ethical and moral values that were once taken for granted have now become moot points: • Social media have proved an unexpected source of pictures, videos, etc. to help the VPD with their investigations and help them identify rioters. • The use of social media in the current investigation process presents limitations and risks of error. • Police and legal systems are overwhelmed by citizens’ involvement in the process of identification through social media websites. • Because of their technical potential, social media can be used in support of mob behavior. • The content of social media was used by citizens to enforce vigilante justice. • Social media is a means of communicating with the public in crisis situations. DISCUSSION In this section we will examine media narratives and the ethical issues they raise, starting from the presumption that the case of the Vancouver riots is an example of a “crisis situation” where a “human crowd”, sends digital material to identify rioters in response to a police request, and feels empowered to enforce justice by itself thanks to social media. We have identified the following main media narratives for this case: • Unverifiable quality - a contribution of questionable quality from social media: it cannot be checked and can lead to unfairness and injustice; considerations regarding the legitimacy of using such material for police investigation. • Institutional Unpreparedness - an unexpected and unmanageable social media contribution to an institutionalised procedure of enquiry: even though it was the authorities who requested it, no procedure seems to be in place to deal with the material received. • Unintended do it yourself society - do it yourself justice: citizens overruling authorities and enforcing justice on their own terms and by their own means. • Unintended do it yourself society - mob behaviour: following other trends, mainly in political contexts, social media showed its potential for prompting people to act. Anyone is entitled to take action and whoever does so decides what constitutes a legitimate motive to act. • Authorised do it yourself society - innocuous use: social media as a means of communication between authorities and citizens. The quality of social media material and legitimacy of its use in law enforcement and charge processes The media narratives highlight the problems related to the governance of crisis situations and in particular the authorities’ use of social media in those situations. Whilst social media have provided an incommensurable trove of data, the use of such media in unexpected ways has disturbed the VPD’s usual process of investigation. The VPD got hold of suspects’ names before finding out exactly what they did and where they did it. Pictures and videos can easily be misinterpreted and police have to confirm the legitimacy of using them. These considerations lead us to examine this issue in terms of quality. In Europe, computer evidence must fulfill a number of criteria. These are admissibility, which means the evidence must conform to certain legal rules before it can be presented in court; authenticity, which means it must be possible to relate it to the incident; completeness, which means it must tell the whole story, not a biased or partial version of it; and reliability, which means its authenticity cannot be questioned (Brezinski, and Killalea, 2002). In the case of the Vancouver riots, it appears that the material posted by social networkers did not tell the whole story. It therefore did not fulfill the completeness and authenticity criteria. We would argue that the most relevant ethical consideration that emerges from this narrative relates to fairness Rizza, et al. Do-it-yourself justice: the 2011 Vancouver Riots Proceedings of the 10 th International ISCRAM Conference – Baden-Baden, Germany, May 2013 T. Comes, F. Fiedrich, S. Fortier, J. Geldermann and T. Müller, eds. 414 and justice, in light of the difficulties it created with regard to institutionalised procedures and the unintended use of technology. Unregulated empowerment Sophisticated technical ability is not needed to use social media to diffuse, publish or use information about a person. In the context of the riots, news media tell us that the VPD asked citizens to provide relevant material that could help them identify rioters. Despite the fact that citizens are supposed to be aware of the law as far as the online publication of “personal information” is concerned, actual awareness of such laws is low. In crisis situations, it is more likely that the law will be flouted and that people will not try to find out what the relevant legal provisions are. This problem is aggravated by the fact that, in this case, an authority asked citizens to contribute (‘to send’) material. This request made citizens feel “authorised” to publish their material. But is it fair to ask citizens to be aware of these legal provisions, let alone to be able to judge what they can do if called on to act by an authority? We would argue that whilst the ethical responsibility for the authenticity of material sent by individuals could be attributed to individuals, accountability for any of the consequences of empowering citizens and involving them in law enforcement remains with the authorities themselves. It is clear that the consequences of “crowd-sourced surveillance” (Samuel, 2011) during the Vancouver riots were neither fully controlled nor thoroughly reflected upon. The ethical considerations that are most relevant in this narrative relate to integrity, responsibility, accountability and fairness. Social media vigilantes The news media narratives shed light on the fuzzy boundaries between supporting police departments and enforcing “vigilante justice”. They also show that the technical potential of social media i.e. instantaneous diffusion of information, tags, etc.) has enabled a shift from supporting the authorities to “do it yourself justice”. News media regard social media vigilantism as a real danger. What happened during the Vancouver riots should not be considered an exception but a real threat to Western democracies (Samuel, 2011). Henry (2011) analyses the Vancouver riots from the legal point of view, reminding readers that exploring legal considerations about the hockey rioters marks “us” as a democratic society. A “do it yourself justice” is not acceptable looking at the consequences of acts (e.g. Velasquez, et al., 2009) and considering that, no matter how bad the circumstances are in a crisis situation “bad ethics” is not the answer (Zack, 2009). Moreover, “do it yourself justice” enforced by vigilante citizens using social media, did not respect normal legal process, in which a rushed judgment is not admissible when evidence is overwhelming (Henry, 2011). The ethical considerations of this narrative are related to fairness and justice, as in the John Locke “rights ethics” (Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2001): “all men equally have the right to punish transgressors” but “men agreed to delegate this function to certain officers”. Then, the Vancouver “do it yourself justice” episode illustrates the infringement of a long-established “social contract” in which the function of establishing the law is assigned to the State. Who decides what an issue is Another interesting issue arising from these events and other events involving the use of social media is issue framing. This is closely connected with the “mob behaviour” narrative, in which any of us can initiate discussion of an issue online and invite others to participate in the discussion. This is particularly pertinent to the idea of a “do it yourself society”. Traditional ways of framing issues are fragmented, with anyone being entitled to voice what is important and relevant, raising ethical concerns around justice, responsibility and accountability. CONCLUSION In these concluding remarks, we draw on ideas of “imagined community” (Anderson, 2006). For example, a “nation” is in important respects “imagined” since each of its members will never know or meet, or even hear of, most of their fellow members, but the image of their communion lives in the mind of each member (Anderson, 2006). The nation is thus considered a “community” through the concept of “fraternity”. Vancouver citizens (the imagined community) reacted to the riots, first by sending digital material to the VPD, and then by trying to find and punish the rioters by themselves. They acted to protect what the “identity” and “reputation” of Rizza, et al. Do-it-yourself justice: the 2011 Vancouver Riots Proceedings of the 10 th International ISCRAM Conference – Baden-Baden, Germany, May 2013 T. Comes, F. Fiedrich, S. Fortier, J. Geldermann and T. Müller, eds. 415 Vancouver’s community against what they saw as an attempt to undermine it. Pictures of rioters published online with the caption “Wanted for crimes against Vancouver” 4 illustrate this sentiment. In response to the riots, Vancouverites who share and belong to the same community of Vancouver have engaged in “do it yourself justice”, authorised by the VPD’s request for digital evidence and emboldened by the potential of social media. Mob behaviour can be exponentially increased by the use of social media: the opportunities they afford “increase the visibility of participation, allow for instantaneous dissemination of information about police and perpetrators to a wide audience” (Heverin, 2011). In this context, it is important for authorities to establish clear rules regarding citizen cooperation in a crisis situation: supporting justice does not mean allowing citizens to substitute the police or other agents of the law. This is of the utmost importance for fairness and the respect of ‘our’ democratic values (Henry, 2011). REFERENCES 1. Anderson, B. (2006) Imagined Communities, London. 2. Brezinski, D. and Killalea, T. (2002) Guidelines for evidence collection and archiving, The Internet Society, February 2002, http://www.ietf.org/rfc/rfc3227.txt [last visit 21/11/2012] 3. Budinger, T. F. and Budinger, M. D. (2006) Ethics of emerging Technologies: Scientific Facts and Moral Challenges. Hoboken, New Jersey: John wiley & sons, Inc. 4. van Dijk, T. A. (1983) Discourse analysis: its development and application to the structure of news, Journal of Communication, Volume 33:2 20–43, Spring 1983. 5. Furlong, J. and Keefe, D. J. (2011)`The Night the City became a Stadium. Independent Review of the 2011 Vancouver Stanley Cup Playoffs Riot. Government of British Columbia Publication. http://www.pssg.gov.bc.ca/vancouverriotreview/docs/riot-review-report.pdf [last visit 21/11/2012] 6. Gorringe, H. and Rosie M. (2011) King mob: perceptions, prescriptions and presumptions about the policing of England's riots, Sociological Research Online, 16 (4) 17, 30 November 2011, http://www.socresonline.org.uk/16/4/17.html [last visit 21/11/2012] 7. Henry, D. Is it illegal to name and shame rioters online?, CBCnews. 20 June, 2011. http://www.cbc.ca/news/canada/story/2011/06/20/f-vp-henry.html [last visit 21/11/2012] 8. Heverin, T. (2011) Ethical concerns of Twitter use for collective crisis response. IEEE Conference Proceedings. pp. 625–626, 23-27 May 2011. http://ieeexplore.ieee.org/stamp/stamp.jsp? tp=&arnumber=5928746 [last visit 21/11/2012] 9. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, (2001) John Locke, April 2001. http://www.iep.utm.edu/locke/ [last visit 21/11/2012] 10. Mullins, S. (2005) Ethical crisis management?, International Journal of Management and Decision Making, Vol. 6, No.3/4 pp. 372 – 381. 11. Samuel, A. (2011) Six keys to putting the crowdsourced surveillance genie back in the lamp, Harvard Business Review, 30 June, 2011. http://blogs.hbr.org/samuel/2011/06/6-ways-to-put-the- crowdsourced.html [last visit 21/11/2012] 12. Svedin L. (Ed.) (2011), Ethical and Crisis Management. Information Age Publishing. 13. Velasquez, M. et al. (2009) A Framework for Thinking Ethically. Santa Clara University. On-line: http://www.scu.edu/ethics/practicing/decision/framework.html [last visit: 21/11/2012] 14. Zack, N. (2009). Ethics for Disaster. Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. 4 See e.g. http://www.techi.com/2011/06/social-media-used-to-identify-vancouver-riot-suspects/ [last visit: 11/02/2013] work_jr2opjt32vgrph3mijq6gp5akm ---- 291-311_EUC_104684.indd Comparative Criminal Justice Beyond Ethnocentricism and Relativism David Nelken University of Macerata, Italy A B S T R A C T How can the study of comparative criminal justice avoid the opposite angers of ethnocentricism and relativism? The problem is examined taking as an example Cavadino and Dignan’s recent analysis of differences in prison rates. The case is made that more attention needs to be given to understanding how different criminal justice systems actually produce prison rates as well as to interpreting the ideas and values that animate those inside and outside the system. K E Y W O R D S Comparative Criminal Justice / Comparative Criminal Procedure / Ethnocentricism and Relativism / Processes of Attrition / Garantismo / Gedogen / Tolerance. Comparative criminal justice: Making sense of difference The task of comparative criminal justice, most scholars would agree, is to com pare and contrast our ways of responding to crime with those practised else where. It also often involves, even if it does not necessarily have to do so, borrowing from, or at least trying to learn from, what is done in other places. It would seem obvious therefore that, if it is to be at all helpful, com- parison requires understanding and interpreting what those in other places are actually trying to do. What I want to show in this paper is that the implications of this apparently banal point are not always straightforward. The reason for this is that it can be difficult not to fall foul of two opposing dangers. On the one hand, there is the risk of being ethnocentric – assuming that what we do, our way of thinking about and responding to crime, is uni- versally shared or, at least, that it would be right for everyone else. On the Volume 6 (4): 291–311: 1477-3708 DOI: 10.1177/1477370809104684 Copyright © 2009 European Society of Criminology and SAGE Publications Los Angeles, London, New Delhi, Singapore and Washington DC www.sagepublications.com ARTICLES 292 European Journal of Criminology 6(4) other hand, there is the temptation of relativism, the view that we will never really be able to grasp what others are doing and that we can have no basis for evaluating whether what they do is right. To get beyond these alternatives requires a careful mix of explanatory and interpretative strategies (Nelken 1994).1 We need to recognize that, although criminal justice practices gain their sense from the setting that shapes them and the conditions with which they have to deal, they can also be understood by outsiders and need to be evaluated according to cosmopolitan and not only local criteria. But this is easier said than done. It is inevitable that our perception of others will be coloured to some extent by our own cultural starting points – even when we say that what we are doing is trying to learn from them. And criminologists do also have their own shared cultural common-sense. We tend to argue that the rise in crime rates is exaggerated by the media and the politicians, that we should avoid creating even more deviance by over-reacting to offending, that the availability of work and decent housing are more effective ways of reducing crime than whatever can be delivered by criminal justice. In the face of the changes brought about by neo-liberalism, we plead instead for policies based on inclusion, solidarity, tolerance and respect for difference. Not least, we recommend that politicians listen to pro- fessionals rather than seeking easy popularity. There may be little to quarrel with in these claims as aspirations. But when our study of other places merely confirms what we already thought was true and right, we need to be aware that we may not have given sufficient care to analysing the simi- larities and differences that may lie behind the practices we are studying. The same applies to the more specific biases that come from our local cultural backgrounds. Policy makers in the Netherlands, for example, tend to look for pragmatic, practically workable solutions to crime – as they do when seeking to resolve other types of problem. In Dutch cultural common- sense, being pragmatic means not being dogmatic, but elsewhere these terms may have a different relationship. In Italy, the term ‘pragmatic’ suggests behaviour that is not guided by principles and that therefore borders on being unprincipled. Which is not to say the Italians in everyday life are not often pragmatic, and the Dutch never principled. Far from it. The point is rather how difficult it can be for us to see the limits of our ways of seeing things. As the American philosopher Morgenbesser reportedly used to say, ‘pragmatism is all right in theory’! But if the question is when it would be appropriate not to be pragmatic, a pragmatic approach itself may not be 1 Francis Pakes (2004: 13ff) suggests that those who favour an exclusively interpretative approach to social life (I am not in fact one of them) must necessarily be relativists. Whether or not this is true is doubtful, but those who rely only on a positivistic strategy certainly do run a high risk of ethnocentrism. Nelken Comparative criminal justice 293 able to provide the answer we need. Likewise, it is impossible to specify, in principle, all the contingencies that may play a role in shaping the everyday application of principles. If we are to come close to grasping successfully what other systems of criminal justice are actually trying to do, we must avoid attributing to them intentions on the basis of what we imagine they should be doing – even if these are the best of intentions. Likewise – but this can be even more tricky – we should be careful not to deduce intentions from the outcomes being achieved. But it is often tempting – especially for the purposes of advancing a given agenda in local debates – to try to do just that. A good current example in my view can be found in some of the arguments being used as part of the important debate concerning the problem of growing punitiveness in responding to crime both in the USA and elsewhere. In briefly reviewing this debate I shall suggest that criminologists from Anglo-American backgrounds engaged in cross-cultural research need to devote more attention to what they and others mean by punitiveness and tolerance. I shall first say something about the so-called ‘punitive turn’ and then describe some recent attempts to link punishment to differences in political economy. In seeking to show the dangers of ethnocentrism, and the way more attention to interpretative questions might help to avoid them, I shall illustrate my argument with accounts of what may be some relatively un- familiar features of penal justice in Italy. The choice of Italy is not only a reflection of the fact that this is the country whose criminal justice system I now know best. Italy is also, surprisingly, the major European country with one of the lowest levels of offenders in prison in proportion to its popu- lation (Proband 2008). The ‘punitive turn’: America as dystopia – Europe as utopia? Criminal justice systems today face many common problems and increas- ingly seem to be responding in similar ways to ‘risk society’ (Beck 1992). As Hans Boutellier puts it, people are now seeking a ‘safety utopia’ (Boutellier 2004). Like all utopias, the attempt to impose this one can be dangerous for those who get in the way. But perhaps it is also dangerous for the rest of us! Hence the concern amongst many criminologists about growing punitiveness. Most of these writers do not argue that prison should be abolished. Still less do they claim that punishment is never necessary or justified, or that tolerance is always the better option – the decreased social tolerance of some forms of criminal or deviant behaviour may even be welcomed. Their con cern is about what Willem De Haan has described as the ‘bad conscience 294 European Journal of Criminology 6(4) of punishment’ (De Haan 1990); the economic and political mobilization of punitiveness – especially, but not only, in the United States – that is described in books with titles such as Crime Control as Industry (Christie 1993), ‘Making Crime Pay’ (Beckett 1997), and, most recently, Governing through Crime (Simon 2007). Why is increasing resort to punishment and, in particular, greater use of prison widely felt to be necessary and appropriate? Even though all the evidence suggests that crime levels have been decreasing, trends in punish- ment, to a large extent, follow their own timing and have their own logic. In his recent influential thesis about what he calls the ‘culture of control’, David Garland (2001) offers a pessimistic account of this development, arguing that ‘penal welfarism’ has been displaced by the politicization of crime and the growth of popular punitiveness. He notes the privileging of public protection and the claim that ‘prison works’, and describes the changes in the emotional tone of crime policy from decency and humanity to insecurity, anger and resentment. What remains controversial, however, is how far what others have called ‘the penal turn’ should be seen as a result of widespread late-modern changes in social and economic conditions, or rather treated as something tied more closely to the political and legal culture of the USA. What some observers see as an essential aspect of late modern- ity others see as ethnocentric projection – an Anglo-American tendency to assume that what others do in foreign places and foreign languages is less import ant, and that they too are bound to come into line eventually. Such critics tell us that we can and must avoid the dystopia (Zedner 2002) of assuming that Europe is also bound to end up with something like the bloated US penal system, which now embraces more than 2 million prisoners. They insist that we need to recognize and explore the differences between the USA and Europe and even within Europe, differences which suggest that there are multiple cultures of control rather than just one culture of control. Some European countries are seen as exemplifying the possibility of maintaining a less punitive climate. Until some years ago, for example, the Netherlands was very much in the group of those countries from which it was proposed to learn how to be less punitive. But things have changed, and it has been calculated that for a period recently the Dutch prison population increased at a faster rate even than that in the United States.2 Now it is the Scandinavian countries that are seen as beacons of tolerance. 2 Its official level of imprisonment, however – like that of other European countries – is still nowhere near the US level, and it has recently again begun to decline. Nelken Comparative criminal justice 295 Punitiveness and political economy What explains the existence of contrasts in cultures of control? A valuable and innovative contribution to answering this question has been provided by Cavadino and Dignan in their book about comparative penal systems (Cavadino and Dignan 2006a). Their analysis has rightly been much praised,3 and has been put to work by other leading writers who are trying to illustrate what they call ‘differences in penal tolerance’ so as to stop the dangerous slide in England and Wales towards an ever-expanding prison system (see e.g. Lacey 2008; Reiner 2007). Ruling out any direct cor relation with cross-national differences in public support for prison sentences, Cavadino and Dignan argue that variations in incarceration rates – which they take as a rough proxy for levels of punitiveness – are related to con- trasting kinds of political economy. As seen in Table 1 (a slightly simplified version of the table that is the linchpin of their thesis), rates of imprison- ment in 12 modern industrial societies vary considerably between what they call neo-liberal, conservative-corporatist, social democratic, and oriental- corporatist types of political economy.4 They argue that the neo-liberal societies have the highest prison rates because they follow social and economic policies that lead to what they describe as ‘exclusionary cultural attitudes towards our deviant and mar- ginalised fellow citizens’ (Cavadino and Dignan 2006a: 23; 2006b: 447). On the other hand, Continental European corporatist societies (which have also been described as ‘coordinated market economies’) and, even more, Scandinavian social democratic societies, are said to ‘pursue more inclusive economic and social policies that give citizens more protection from un- fettered market forces’ and to ‘see offenders as needing resocialisation which is the responsibility of the community as a whole’ (Cavadino and Dignan 2006a: 24; 2006b: 448). Other authors have since followed up their approach. Lacey (2008), for example, seeks to explain why what she calls ‘coordinated market economies’ have the opposite effects to neo-liberal develop ments, and argues that multi-party political systems are less likely to lead to appeals to populism than two-party systems. She also makes, though does not develop, the telling point that the corporatist countries 3 There is much to admire in Cavadino and Dignan’s pioneering work, and I cannot attempt to do justice to it here. For example, they also link punitive attitudes to levels of prison privatization and the age at which young people are held to be criminally liable – though here too some caution is needed. For example, Scotland has an advanced welfare system for juveniles despite criminal liability beginning at 8. 4 In addition to quoting most of the 2002/3 figures that they drew on in their 2006 book and article, I have added, for comparison, the current 2008 figures. These are not out of line with their argument. 296 European Journal of Criminology 6(4) (and also the social democratic ones) that are so good, relatively speaking, at offering an ‘inclusive’ approach to their own citizens are perhaps less equipped than neo-liberal ones for dealing with the challenge of ‘outsider’ crimes by (illegal) immigrants (see Solivetti 2004, 2007). Problems in comparing prison rates Cavadino and Dignan’s thesis is certainly very convincing, even if it is not the only way of using differences in rates of incarceration as indicators of comparative punitiveness.5 Neo-liberalism in the USA and Europe does Table 1 Imprisonment rates per 100,000 in 12 countries, 2002/3 and 2008 2002/3 2008 Neo-liberal countries USA 701 756 South Africa 402 334 New Zealand 155 185 England and Wales 141 152 Australia 115 129 Conservative-corporatist countries Italy 100 92 Germany 98 89 Netherlands 100 100 France 93 96 Social democracies Sweden 73 74 Finland 70 64 Oriental-corporatist countries Japan 53 63 Sources: 2002/3 – Cavadino and Dignan (2006a: 22); 2008 – King’s College London, International Centre for Prison Studies, World Prison Brief, URL (accessed 3 March 2009): http://www.kcl.ac.uk/depsta/law/research/icps/worldbrief/wpb_stats.php. 5 Marcelo Aebi, when offering his annual interpretations of Council of Europe penal statistics, simply uses geographical criteria to contrast groups of countries with different levels of incarceration, distinguishing, from high to low, Eastern Europe, the Caucasian area, Central Europe, Western Europe, South Eastern Europe, Southern Europe, and the Scandinavian countries. Although certainly less ambitious and less illuminating than Cavadino and Dignan’s approach, the similarities in prison rates within each area are striking and are likely explained by wider socio-economic-political similarities and (or?) by which countries are treated locally Nelken Comparative criminal justice 297 seem to be associated with factors that lead to less concern with ‘including’ potential offenders, and its rise coincides in many of these countries with greater use of the prison. But, insofar as it claims to be an explanation of punitive ness, it should be noted that the authors actually define neo- liberalism as including punitive attitudes. In addition, their explanation may be limited in its range. Countries such as China make very heavy use of prison without being neo-liberal. Others, such as Russia (as well as South Africa, which is one of the countries they seek to explain), have seen a rise in neo-liberalism together with a reduction in the use of prison. This suggests that a wider variety of variables than those connected to neo-liberalism can lead to higher or lower punitiveness. Even if we take the argument on its own terms, however, there are a number of questions that need to be raised about relying on prison rates as an index of punitiveness. A concept as intricate as punitiveness is poorly represented by a single indicator such as the detention rate. Are crime levels the same in each of the countries being compared? What do prison rates refer to? Why is there so much volatility over time? Do prison rates only reflect factors internal to the countries concerned? How large a part of the ex planation of prison rates is to be attributed to differences in criminal procedure? Take first the problem of crime levels. For Table 1 to make sense we must assume that levels are roughly similar in each of the countries being com pared. Higher prison rates in countries dealing with higher levels of crime would not make news, and we could not easily say we were compar- ing levels of punitiveness if the crime threat being faced was different. There are reasons to think, for example, that England and Wales does have higher levels of some crimes (e.g. burglary), while Japan certainly has overall lower levels of crime. Perhaps more important, it is strange that the good things about belonging to more inclusive welfare-oriented or social democratic societies do not also reduce the level or severity of crimes being committed (and not only shape the response to them). But in that case can we still say that a country is, relatively, less ‘punitive’ if it faces less crime? Above all, we need to know how to get to grips with the variety of factors within as exemplars to conform to. It is unclear if such differences always coincide with contrasts in degrees of neo-liberalism. In complete contrast, Jan Van Dijk, a leading Dutch criminologist, has compiled a worldwide ‘punitiveness scale’ that pays scant attention to geography but subtracts the relative rank of countries in annual homicide rates from their rank in levels of incarceration (i.e. greater punitiveness means having more people in prison than would be expected from the number of murders in the country). On this criterion, Finland, Sweden and Norway turn out to be lenient but so does Australia, whereas Germany and Italy turn out to be relatively punitive (see Van Dijk 2007: 270 and 370–4). This intriguing if somewhat crude strategy begs the question of whether relative punitiveness is in fact correlated with crime levels, and in any case places too much reliance on only one crime measure. 298 European Journal of Criminology 6(4) the penal process itself that actually produce its prison rates. Many of the countries that have lower overall rates – Sweden for example, or Switzerland (or the Netherlands in its glorious period) – use shorter prison terms, but actually send relatively more people to prison than those with higher overall rates. Does this show less punitiveness than sending fewer people for longer periods? It certainly complicates any argument we may want to make about punitiveness and inclusiveness.6 The empirical basis for the argument may be less solid than it seems. Table 1 offers snapshots from 2002/ 3 and 2008, but prison rates in different countries in earlier periods have not always varied in ways that confirm the argument. And they have again diverged from it more recently. For example, after the Second World War Finland’s rate went down sharply from one far higher than its Scandinavian neighbours (187 per 100,000, Lappi-Seppälä 2001),7 whereas the Netherlands, as already mentioned, went in the opposite direction so as to give it, for a while, one of the highest rates in Europe.8 Even the USA had a moderate level of use of prison until the 1970s. According to 2006 figures, Italy, with a rate of only 65.2 per 100,000 had the lowest prison population amongst Continental European countries (Proband 2008). But the explanation for this does not lie with the generosity of its welfare or work- training systems (welfare payments mainly go to pay pensions). Its current low rate owes a lot to the recent indulto (or col lective pardon), which freed over a third of its prison inmates.9 Although this is a particularly striking example, the importance of the indulto under- lines the centrality of the criminal justice process to understanding the significance of prison rates. It is impossible to understand the figures for France, for example, without taking its amnesties and pardons into account. Aside from the difficult task of trying to ‘purify’ comparative figures of such interventions, it could also be argued that it is fruitless, since the willingness to use amnesties could itself be taken as an illustration of tolerance. Such volatility is not always easy to reconcile with claims about the dependence of such rates on underlying basic differences in political 6 Commentators on prison rates such as Aebi distinguish between ‘stock’ (how many are held in prison), ‘flow’ (how many see the inside of a prison) and the average sentence lengths in prison (for how long prisoners are held in custody). Punitiveness rankings vary considerably depending on which of these criteria is selected. 7 Finland’s rate of imprisonment declined to 154 per 100,000 in 1960, 113 in 1970, 106 in 1980, 69 in 1990 and 55 in 2000. 8 The Netherlands’ rate was only 84 in every 100,000 in 1999 but then increased in a few years to higher than 130 – occasioning an extensive academic commentary seeking to ‘explain’ this new punitiveness. The rate has again declined more recently. See Aebi and Stadnic (2007). 9 Although the indulto postdates the Council of Europe’s 2005 annual survey, the small print indicates that it was somehow taken into account, and Italy is indicated as a country that has seen a recent 36 percent decline in its prison population. Its prison population is now again rising and is predicted to shortly reach pre-indulto levels. Nelken Comparative criminal justice 299 economy. But, apart from anything else, countries’ prison rates are not just a reflection of their attitudes to offenders or potential offenders. They are also a product of reflexive responses by politicians and policy makers to their per ceptions of where their country stands in relation to other places. Thus the reduction in Finnish prison sentences and the increase in the Dutch level were in part responses to the prison rates in countries to which they thought they could and would be compared. Roy Walmsley, an adviser to the United Nations, whose figures were the source of Cavadino and Dignan’s table (see Walmsley 1999), urges all countries to shape their criminal justice prac tices so as to aim at a rate of no more than 100 prisoners per 100,000 of the population,10 and so obviously assumes that this can be brought about irrespective of more fundamental changes in a country’s political economy. Tables such as theirs, in addition to their role as explanatory aids, are therefore capable of changing policy – and are often intended to do so. They should be treated not just as a resource for explaining differences in prison rates but also as social artefacts whose func- tion lies in their utility for local struggles about penal practices. But my main concern here is not to point to the difficulties or advant- ages of using international statistics as such, but rather to ask how research on comparative incarceration rates can help us rethink our approaches to the possible sources of punitiveness and leniency rather than only reinforce what we already think and value. Criminologists who attempt to explain which states in the USA have the highest prison rates typically single out correlations with factors such as lower welfare levels, a lack of effort to ensure economic equality, and low public participation. These are all mat- ters that they tend to consider negative factors in their own right. But the so-called ‘evil causes evil’ fallacy may artificially restrict explanations of punishment as much as it does those of crime (see Cohen 1970)11 – all the more so in cross-cultural contexts. Applied to Cavadino and Dignan’s argu- ment, there does seem to be something ethnocentric about a thesis so well suited to telling policy makers in countries affected by neo-liberalism that evidence from other countries shows us that only more welfare provision and government regulation of the economy can provide a prophylactic against punitiveness. More may be going on than the adoption of a more or a less inclusive approach to (potential) offenders. A cultural propensity to inclusion may 10 Interestingly, Walmsley’s (2003) recommendations of how to reach this goal include avoiding short prison sentences even though the countries with the lowest rates include ones that make most use of such sentences. 11 I do not of course want to argue that ‘evil’ factors are never responsible for ‘evil’ out- comes – and vice versa – only to suggest that such cultural bias can prevent us seeing other possibilities. 300 European Journal of Criminology 6(4) be, in some sense, a relevant cross-cultural factor. The Dutch did pioneer a sharp reduction in the use of prison (Downes 1988), and the Italians too were leaders in the de-carceration movement, which aimed to have mental patients and others treated in the community rather than in total institutions. But the sense we give to this can be fully appreciated only by learning much more about the countries concerned. It is controversial how far the rate of immigration affects prison rates. But it is certainly important to bear in mind that some of the Scandinavian countries with low prison rates have experienced relatively small flows of immigration, or have even done their best to limit ‘economic migration’. It is also hard to learn much from a table that suggests that such differ- ent places as the Netherlands and Italy are equally punitive – and implies that this is for similar reasons of political economy. Compared with the Netherlands, for example, Italy’s inclusiveness has less to do with the guid- ing role of the regulatory state than it does with attitudes of low respect for the legality mandated by the national state, combined with a cultural emphasis on forgiveness, solidarity and fraternalism deriving from current local interpretations of a strong Catholic heritage and left-wing ideologies (Nelken 2000). Importantly, neither of Italy’s two leading belief systems allows individual victims of crime to occupy the moral high ground. In terms of socio economic factors, rather than pointing to political economy as such (even though in fact Italian criminologists have been pioneers in this style of explanation), it is important to recognize the continuing centrality in Italy not only of the family and the extended family (especially important with respect to the handling of juvenile delinquency) but also of family-like groups in maintaining social order in many sectors of public and private life. Nor is this necessarily evidence of Continental European ‘corporatist’ collab oration between business and government. Many of those helping to maintain ‘order’ in the southern regions of Italy are actually organized criminals! The importance of courts and criminal procedure in Italy To show why it is unwise to look for causes of high and low punitiveness only in the factors that are highlighted in Cavadino and Dignan’s thesis, I shall now examine, using Italy as an illustration, the question of the place that needs to be given in any explanation of punitiveness to the role of the criminal justice system itself. It is easy to see that political economy can shape punitiveness only through mediating variables.12 Yet the role of the 12 Cavadino and Dignan, who are continuing to develop their ideas, now call for more exploration of the intermediate factors that connect political economy to punishment – including crime levels, general culture, media culture, political culture and political institutions (Cavadino and Dignan 2008). Nelken Comparative criminal justice 301 criminal process itself remains somewhat ambiguous. Even if what happens inside the criminal justice complex ultimately makes all the difference, is this part of the ‘why’ or only the ‘how’ of punitiveness? How can we decide whether the criminal process is the dependent variable in our explanation or (also) an independent one? Consideration of the Italian case gives us reason to see criminal procedure as an independent or at least semi-autonomous variable in its own right – and not merely as a conduit for wider economic and political factors or changes. But – and this constitutes a further challenge for Cavadino and Dignan’s argument – the degree of such autonomy is itself a sociocultural variable. There are significant differences between countries such as Italy and Anglo- American countries with regard to how far it is thought constitutionally appropriate for criminal justice to be responsive to political direction or to social expectations. This has obvious implications for the extent to which, at the level of everyday decision-making by judges and prosecutors, the criminal justice system seeks to defend its ‘relative’ autonomy from both political and public pressures. Drawing on her knowledge of German arrangements, Lacey (2008) suggests that it is collaboration between politicians, policy makers and courts that is likely to keep prison rates down. But the Italian experience suggests that it can also be the refusal of such collaboration that can lead to this result. The main resistance in Italy to the latest efforts by politicians to encourage the mass criminalization of illegal immigrants comes from a uniquely strong corps of self -governing and independent judges and prosecutors,13 whose priorities are often different from those of both the politicians and the public. It is only by looking at criminal procedure that we can make sense of the paradox of why, despite many reasons that could lead us to expect the opposite, Italy can occupy an average and sometimes low rung in prison rates amongst major European countries. This is a country with an enormous number of criminal laws, many of which are regularly – even routinely – breached at all levels of society. Penal rules and judicial interventions are often relied on as a substitute for political and policy-led decision-making, given that other forms of civil or administrative regulation work (even more) poorly. In four regions of the country, powerful organized crime groups control or subject to their ‘taxes’ large parts of the economy and often con- dition what goes on in regional and local politics. Newspapers are full of 13 Even after the reform of criminal procedure was supposed to have moved Italy towards the accusatorial model, prosecutors and judges form part of the same category, with similar constitutional guarantees of independence and immovability, and are entitled to shift (subject to conditions) from one task to another. There are increasing pressures to introduce the so- called ‘separation of careers’, but this is politically highly controversial because many see it as the route to reducing prosecutors’ independence from political influence. 302 European Journal of Criminology 6(4) crime news, and criminal prosecution can be a potent weapon for assigning stigma. In the so-called Tangentopoli anti-corruption investigations of the 1990s, all the established parties of government were swept from power through the enforcement of laws concerning election finance and corruption of public works contracts, even if few of these individuals stayed in prison for long. Over the recent years in which prison rates have fallen, illegal immi gration has continued to increase, as has the tendency for the police to concentrate their attention on the crimes of immigrants as easy targets. What is more, prosecution in Italy is constitutionally obligatory; so there is no easy way out by using formally mandated types of diversion. So how is it possible that prison rates have sunk so low? In Italy’s case – though I would claim that some of the same mechan- isms are also often significant elsewhere – the answer is that this has little to do with levels of welfare or a state project aimed at the inclusion of marginal individuals, but has everything to do with the operations of its system of justice. Prison rates are low because of processes of attrition; although many cases start out, few arrive at a conclusion. All systems of criminal justice are to some degree intended to be selective (as seen in the now famous distinc- tion in Anglo-American literature between the requirements of ‘due process’ and the objectives of ‘crime control’). But systems differ between themselves (and over time) in the way they construct and operate such selectivity. In Italy, the typical procedural guarantees of the accusatorial system (centring on the forensic contest of the trial) that were introduced in the 1989 reform of criminal procedure were simply added to the ones that belong to the inqui sitorial tradition. This means that even quite minor cases go through a series of procedural hoops and are reviewed by a large number of judges, and there are two stages of appeal (the first stage being a retrial on the facts). There are complex rules about informing the accused and his/her lawyers of trial hearings at each stage of the proceedings and extensive periods are allowed for them to prepare their defence each time. It is not infrequent for such notifications to go astray, especially where there is more than one accused and lawyer involved. All this has obvious repercussions in terms of the time cases take to reach final disposal in Italy. Crucially, the so-called ‘prescription’, or statute of limitations, period after which criminal proceedings become null and void continues to run until the Cassation court has given its final verdict. And this can sometimes take over 10 years.14 Partly under the shock of the Tangentopoli investigations, in which politicians were the main targets, laws 14 This period after which ‘prescription’ sets in varies with the severity of the offence. Prime Minister Berlusconi is among those who have benefited from this procedural nullification of criminal charges. Nelken Comparative criminal justice 303 were passed that allowed those sentenced to less than three years in prison to apply to be put instead under what is often little more than nominal social work tutelage outside prison. Likewise, resources are stretched when it comes to supervising those let out on parole. This formed the larger back- ground against which a large-scale indulto – or collective pardon – was passed by the centre–left government in 2006 (after a long period in which the events of Tangentopoli had made the use of ‘amnesties’ politically unacceptable). Many of the procedural benefits of the Italian criminal justice system are not available to illegal immigrants ‘caught in the act’ of committing crimes, and it is these offenders (and low-level drug dealers) who now tend to fill the prisons. ‘Security’ has also become an ever more important polit ical issue, as shown with the return of a centre–right government in 2008 whose campaign played on linked concerns over immigration and crime.15 Although the Northern League and the ex-fascist National Alliance parties, junior members/allies of Berlusconi’s Liberty Party, had strongly emphasized crime issues even before, it is only recently that the issue of ‘street crime’ has become such an important part of both national and local politics.16 Overlooking the considerable cross-party support at the time it was passed,17 the new government was also able to exploit the un- po pularity of the latest indulto. This measure is likely to have increased crime levels, not least because those let out of prison were not provided with any incentive to reform themselves. But it is still not clear how far the new government will really tighten up on the kind of medium-level crimes typically committed by Italian offenders. Whether this happens again seems less dependent on shifts towards neo-liberalism than on the extent to which politicians can be satisfied that they will not be in the firing line of any expedited proceedings.18 But is Italy just a special case? (As Mrs Thatcher liked to say, when characterizing various countries in the European Union – ‘and then there’s Italy’.) Its politics may be somewhat unusual, but I would argue that 15 Until very recently the Italian expression that encompassed conventional crimes including burglary, rape and robbery was ‘micro-criminality’, used as a broad contrast to corruption, terrorism and organized crime, which threaten the state itself. 16 Directly elected local mayors, as much on the left as on the right, have been vocal about the measures they are taking to maintain local order using local municipal police agents, even if they do not officially have responsibility for the enforcement of criminal justice. 17 The indulto was widely seen as having been motivated by politicians of the right and the left (then in power) looking after their friends. But it was justified at the time in terms of prison overcrowding and carried the express approval of Pope Jean Paul II. 18 One of the first acts of the Berlusconi government elected in 2008 was to pass a law that sought to block for a year all proceedings in which the possible prison sentence was less than 10 years. This ‘happened’ to have the effect of interrupting one court case in which the Premier was himself involved. 304 European Journal of Criminology 6(4) criminal procedure and case-attrition are also a large part of the explanation of how other countries with low prison rates kept them low in the past – or still do so. Germany, for example, diverts around half of its prosecutions, and France in the 1980s and 1990s repeatedly resorted to amnesties as a response to prison overcrowding. The Netherlands and Switzerland used to send offenders home to wait until a place was ready for them in prison. At a minimum therefore we will have to add differences in criminal procedure to the range of explanatory factors canvassed by Cavadino and Dignan.19 But the more we emphasize the role of this factor as an explanation in its own right, the more it becomes difficult to draw a line between, on the one hand, the broader political and economic factors that they treat as their independent variables and, on the other, the dependent variable – prison rates – that their independent variables are intended to explain. The cultural meanings of punitiveness and tolerance A second set of issues concerns the cross-cultural meaning of Cavadino and Dignan’s dependent variable. The observer may choose to define ‘punitive- ness’ and ‘tolerance’ by fiat in terms of prison rates. But in some societies these responses may not even be thought to lie on the same continuum (Nelken 2006). There are many other questions to be clarified. Is tolerance to be seen as the outcome of deliberate choice – for example, the willingness to organize welfare interventions – or does it extend to deliberate (or even negligent) non-enforcement of available sanctions? Who is being said to be punitive or tolerant – politicians, legal professionals or the public? With respect to what sort of behaviour are these terms being applied? Are we talking of neutral ‘facts’ or of value judgements (and whose judgements count)? In sum, it is moot how far we can compare punitiveness and tolerance in different cultures without specifying what (various) actors in each of the societies concerned mean by these terms. Those who compare prison rates seek to avoid this problem by deducing intentions from outcomes. But if we ignore intentions it becomes difficult to be sure that we are comparing like with like. For example, is the effort to ‘change’ individuals, an aim that formed a central part of the ideology of the welfare-rehabilitative ap proach to offenders, a more or a less punitive intervention than the use of prison? Or is it really irrelevant that what I call tolerance you may call permissive- ness, indulgence, favouritism, neglect, indifference, impunity, denial or collusion? 19 Lacey (2008) seems to opt for this solution. Nelken Comparative criminal justice 305 It is in pursuing this sort of interpretative enquiry that comparative research risks the opposite problem, that of relativism. We are told for example that in the Netherlands the term gedogen is not readily translatable into English or any other language. ‘The term is Dutch. The concept is Dutch, and its application only works in Holland.’20 Gedogen does not correspond, for example, to the English term ‘tolerance’ because that can also be passive, whereas the Dutch concept refers to an open-eyed tolerance – a matter of government policy. Comparison with Italy reveals even more significant differences. In the Netherlands, gedogen lies behind official willingness to accommodate exceptions to the law. But in Italy the state can never explicitly approve such accommodation because of the fear that the law will then be bent to the interests of those who wish to achieve immu nity for their own misdeeds while targeting their opponents.21 Italian commentators speak less about being ‘tolerant’ than of the need to subject the criminal process to strict procedural requirements or garanzie.22 But, in practice, ‘tolerance’ as non-enforcement comes about de facto because the legislative body tends to multiply offences at the same time as doing nothing about the considerable difficulties that exist when it comes to enforcing them. Sometimes government impotence may also merge into collusion with elite crime – what has been described as ‘ruling through leniency’ (Melossi 1994). More generally, de facto toleration may be a way of currying popular favour through laxity in enforcing rules and a readiness to accept amends after the event. But attention to these contrasts in the social meanings of tolerance does not have to lead us to a relativist approach. Such a theoretical posi- tion would rule out the possibility of even grasping the existence of these differences. And it would miss the point that penal approaches are often highly contested within the societies concerned, and that perceptions of their acceptability change over time – in part because of exposure to prac- tices in other societies. Despite often ‘ruling through leniency’, Italy has also seen major investigations into political corruption and considerable suc cesses in the fight against the Mafia. On the other hand, despite a tend- ency to distrust the state and to side with those who suffer its vexations, there is now increasing ambivalence (mobilized by much of the media) 20 Taken from the website of the philosophy department of Erasmus University in Rotterdam. Of course, this term also gets its sense as part of a larger semantic field including, amongst others, the key term beleid; see Blankenburg and Bruinsma (1995). 21 In the same way, the Italian term for ‘discretionary’ is used rarely in a positive sense but rather as the semantic equivalent of ‘arbitrariness’. 22 Ferrajoli (1989). A leading Dutch critical criminologist, René Van Swaaningen, argued strongly that garantismo represented a key idea for all critical criminologists to take up (Van Swaaningen 1997). 306 European Journal of Criminology 6(4) towards the continued ‘tolerance’ of everyday crime through attrition, or the ‘inexplicable’ way in which even alleged serious criminals can find them- selves still at large while awaiting trial or benefit in other ways from what seem like excessive procedural formalities. Such re-thinking is seen in the increasing currency of terms such as buonismo (pretentious generosity at others’ expense), perdonismo (being too ready to forgive everything) or garanzie pelose (so-called ‘hairy’ procedural guarantees, which are seen by some as measures pretending to protect the accused’s rights but really aiming to create a system whereby it will be possible, if needed, to get certain accused people ‘off the hook’ at all costs). There would also be more to be said about the changing relationship between tolerance of offending, on the one hand, and tolerance of sexual deviance, moral ambiguity and cultural difference, on the other. It has been argued that, in late modernity, tolerance for some kinds of deviance (for example sexual deviance) may have increased, but that there is now less willing ness to reform and reintegrate those who engage in offending (Young 1999). This process clearly varies from place to place (and disap- proval of offending may often be a covert way of refusing difference). In the Netherlands, the differences between the two kinds of tolerance, and the way they have evolved recently, is well evidenced by the late Pim Fortuyn’s flamboyant display of an alternative sexual lifestyle combined with his in- sistence on the threat represented by Muslim immigration. Such changes in what Cavadino and Dignan describe as ‘attitudes towards inclusion’ have indeed affected the possibility of keeping prison rates down. Gedogen no longer has the widespread support it had (Buruma 2007). But once again, even if such changes in the cultural climate are undoubtedly themselves also influenced by developments in economic and political conditions, they are not simply reducible to them. Conclusion Just as it would be ethnocentric for Americans to assume that European criminal justice does or must work like that in the USA, for them, or English-speaking writers in general, to assume that European societies have fewer people in prison because they possess more regulated types of polit- ical economy may also be misleading (Nelken 2003). Ethnocentrism can be a problem not only where we think our practices are the best, but also where we assume too quickly that the others from whom we wish to learn are acting on the basis of what we think would be best practice (Cain 2000). Adopting an approach that attempts explicitly to get beyond ethnocentrism and relativism shows that simply calling for more of the solidarity and Nelken Comparative criminal justice 307 inclusiveness that is assumed to characterize other societies with lower prison rates is the kind of short-cut that can easily miss the point. Learning from what others do is not so straightforward. On closer acquaintance we may well find that we like the outcome achieved by other systems of criminal justice, but not the means they use to get there – or vice versa. But this message is not as negative as it might seem. Not only are there many things that can be learned from others, there are some matters that can only be learned from others. Reforms that emerge from within the same society often tend to reproduce the problems they are being asked to solve – precisely because they come from the same culture. Thus, in England and Wales – or the Netherlands – the answer to failures in the system is normally thought to be even more concern about efficiency. In Italy it is usually a re- thinking of ‘values’ or principles that is invoked as the way forward. Often the best practice for us to learn from may therefore not always be best practice as such, but that which stretches our imagination about what is possible. Moving a little nearer to what we would otherwise never normally think of doing may be just what we need. And even learning what not to do can be useful, especially where this helps us to understand better why we make the sometimes hard choices we do. In all this, interpreting what others are actually trying to do is essential even if – or especially if – the social actors we are studying do not have, nor could have, all the answers to our – or even to their – problems. If we are to intervene in a helpful way in public debates and policy-making, we must be able to engage with what actors think they are doing, and why it makes sense to them (insofar as it does so). I offer two examples to close with. I am currently engaged in comparative research into the handling of juvenile delinquency in England and Wales. This jurisdiction currently has one of the highest rates in Europe for the incarceration of juveniles and cer- tainly much higher than that of Italy. If you ask the legal actors and others involved in the system why this is so, you will not usually hear them saying anything about trying to be punitive or intolerant. Rather, they claim to be doing their best to help children before they get into further trouble.23 The number of youngsters ending up in prison is increasing as a result of government insistence on a quick through-put of cases. This is because per- sistent offenders run through the gamut of non-penal alternatives more quickly. But, again, this policy was ostensibly put in place in the interests of the offenders themselves. Different working assumptions lie behind the levels of tolerance or leniency in dealing with young people in different 23 Even if, for some of those involved, it feels like a Faustian pact by which they have to agree to the risk of increasing criminalization in return for continuing access to welfare resources for deprived youths. 308 European Journal of Criminology 6(4) places. In England and Wales it is thought that children will not easily grow out of delinquency without official intervention. In Italy, on the other hand, there is a legally enshrined presupposition that in the majority of cases they will do so. On the other hand, Italy has one of the highest rates in Europe for the pro portion of illegal immigrants in prison, usually sent there for low-level property offences and drug-dealing. Why is it that these offenders do not benefit from the many procedural possibilities for delaying trial or avoiding prison? In part this is because they lack the legal competence and assist- ance to do so. But, in addition, official actors do not always interpret the procedural possibilities for leniency that do exist in their favour. Italian law says that first offenders sentenced to terms of less than two years should normally have their prison sentences suspended, on the legal assumption that they have not offended before and are unlikely to do so again. Should this provision also be applied to illegal immigrants? According to some magistrates, immigrants are entitled to the same protections as anyone else; it is not their job to take into account sociological considerations. What is at stake is a matter of basic fairness and formal equality of treatment. Other judges think that such offenders may well have already had a criminal record abroad before immigrating; they also argue that it is unrealistic to assume that a person without home or work will not be tempted to re-offend and that if measures are not taken to stop offenders now they will do their best to disappear. Although both views are held within the magistracy, the first, more lenient, approach is being steadily undermined by political and media pressure. In both of these examples, labelling one view ‘punitive’ and the other ‘tolerant’ is not particularly helpful. The actors in each criminal justice system are up against the well-known difficulties of trying to find penal solutions to what are in fact larger social problems. Insofar as they have room for manoeuvre, their choices will reflect their conceptions of what courts can and should do in these situations (choices that may not be con- sistent across the range of different kinds of social problems). This said, when it comes to the evaluation of criminal justice practices, whether actors think they are being tolerant or punitive is not the end of the matter. We can, do and should make our own defeasible claims about other people’s ideas and actions even where they would reject our interpretations. Not only self-confessed racists are racists! So it can make sense in some contexts to describe people as tolerant even if they do not intend to be (and vice- versa). It can be helpful to show actors that things could be done differently, and that they are already being done differently, elsewhere. Increasing their awareness of this can help unpack the self-fulfilling assumptions of the Nelken Comparative criminal justice 309 criminal justice systems they belong to. But we should not overestimate their ignorance of matters elsewhere,24 and we need to exercise great caution in substituting our accounts of what they are trying to do for their own. In Italy, despite (or because of?) its low prison rate, ‘tolerance’ – or the local equivalents – has recently come to be seen by many as less and less something to be proud of but rather as evidence of the neglect of existing and potential victims. As one influential editorialist in a mainstream newspaper recently commented, in criticizing the latest indulto, ‘what right does the state have to pardon identified offenders at the expense of the unidentified victims who will suffer from the crimes that they will commit once released’. He ends by insisting that ‘public opinion is not bloodthirsty. It does not dream of taking revenge on Cain. Simply, it has eyes also for Abel and sees the solitude in which he has been left’ (Ricolfi 2007, my translation). To compete with this sort of rhetoric – aimed cleverly at reducing the religious and cultural aversion in Italy to what might otherwise might be seen as putting law at the service of ‘vendetta’ – one possible strategy could be to insist that there can be more constructive ways of punishing than prison. But alternatives to prison do have their own costs and difficulties, and they are hard to apply in the case of offenders who have arrived in a country as irregular – and supposedly unwanted – immigrants. What seems undeniable is that, in the current penal climate, if we are to propose the adoption of different practices we will normally need to do more than merely show that they are – in their outcome – less punitive. Timing is everything. Acknowledgements This article is a much revised version of a paper ‘Comparative Criminal Justice: Beyond Ethnocentrism and Relativism’, given as a Keynote speech to the First Conference on Assessing Deviance, Crime and Prevention in Europe’, CRIMPREV network of excellence, Brussels, Belgium, 8 February 2007; as a plenary presentation at the European Society of Criminology conference at Bologna, Italy, 26 September 2007; and as the Visiting Wiarda Chair inaugural lecture at the University of Utrecht, the Netherlands, 13 June 2008. I should like to thank the journal’s anonymous referees for their valuable comments. 24 It is not enough just to point out to English magistrates that things are done differently in Italy. Some then reply that this is possible there only because of the strength of Italian family life, whereas in England they are unable to count on such family support. 310 European Journal of Criminology 6(4) References Aebi, M. and Stadnic, N. (2007). Council of Europe annual penal statistics. SPACE 1: 2005 Survey on prison populations. Strasbourg, 30 January 2007;. URL (accessed 5 March 2009): http://www.coe.int/t/e/legal_ affairs/legal_co-operation/prisons_and_alternatives/statistics_space_i/ C o u n c i l % 2 0 o f % 2 0 E u r o p e _ S P A C E % 2 0 I % 2 0 - % 2 0 2 0 0 5 % 2 0 - %20final%20version.pdf. Beck, U. (1992). Risk society. London: SAGE. Beckett, K. (1997). Making crime pay. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Blankenburg, E. and Bruinsma, F. (1995). Dutch legal culture, 2nd edn. Deventer: Elsevier. Boutellier, H. (2004). The safety utopia. Berlin: Springer. Buruma, Y. (2007). Dutch tolerance. On drugs, prostitution and euthanasia. In M. Tonry and C. Bijleveld (eds) Crime and justice in the Netherlands, 73–113. Chicago,IL: University of Chicago Press. Cain, M. (2000). Orientalism, occidentalism and the sociology of crime. British Journal of Criminology 40, 239–60. Cavadino, M. and Dignan, J. (2006a). Penal systems: A comparative approach. London: SAGE. Cavadino, M. and Dignan, J. (2006b). Penal policy and political economy. Crimin- ology and Criminal Justice 6, 435–56. Cavadino. M. and Dignan, J. (2008). Penal comparisons: Puzzling relations. Paper presented at Worldwide Universities Network Colloquium on International and Comparative Criminal Justice and Urban Governance: Policy Convergence, Divergence and New Justice Paradigms. University of Leeds, 26–28 June 2008. Christie, N. (1993). Crime control as industry. London: Routledge. Cohen, A. (1970). Multiple factor approaches. In Marvin Wolfgang et al. (eds) The sociology of crime and delinquency, 123–6. New York: Wiley. De Haan, W. (1990). The politics of redress. London: Unwin. Ferrajoli, L. (1989). Diritto e ragione. Rome: Laterza. Downes, D. (1988). Contrasts in tolerance. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Garland, D. (2001). The culture of control. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Lacey, N. (2008). The prisoners’ dilemma: Political economy and punishment in contemporary democracies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lappi-Seppälä, T. (2001). Sentencing and punishment in Finland. The decline of the re pressive ideal. In M. H. Tonry and R. S. Frase (eds) Sentencing and sanctions in western countries, 92–150. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Melossi, D. (1994). The economy of illegalities. Normal crimes, elites and social control in comparative analysis. In D. Nelken (ed.) The futures of criminology, 202–19. London: SAGE. Nelken, D. (1994). The future of comparative criminology. In D. Nelken (ed.) The futures of criminology, 220–44. London: SAGE. Nelken, D. (2000) Telling difference: Of crime and criminal justice in Italy. In D. Nelken, Contrasting criminal justice, 233–64. Aldershot: Dartmouth. Nelken, D. (2003). Beyond compare? Criticising the American way of law. Law and Social Inquiry 28, 181–213. Nelken Comparative criminal justice 311 Nelken, D. (2006). Italian juvenile justice: Tolerance, leniency or indulgence? Youth Justice 6, 107–28. Pakes, F. (2004). Comparative criminal justice. Cullompton: Willan. Proband, S. C. (2008). European populations stable. Newsletter of the European Society of Criminology 7, May; URL (accessed 5 March 2009): http://www. esc-eurocrim.org/newsletter/May08ESCnewsletter.pdf. Reiner, R. (2007). Political economy, crime and criminal justice. In M. Maguire, R. Morgan and R. Reiner (eds) Oxford handbook of criminology, 4th edn, 341–80. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Ricolfi, L. (2007). La sicurezza scotta. La Stampa, 13 October. Simon, J. (2007). Governing through crime. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Solivetti, L. M. (2004). Immigrazione, integrazione e crimine in Europa. Bologna: Il Mulino. Solivetti, L. M. (2007). Societies poor in civic virtues: A cross-national analysis model on immigrants’ integration and host country characteristics. In Società Italiana di Statistica (ed.) Proceedings of the 2007 Intermediate Conference Risk and Prediction, 107–18. Padova: Cleup. Van Dijk, J. (2007). The world of crime. London: SAGE. Van Swaaningen, R. (1997). Critical criminologies: Visions from Europe. London: SAGE. Walmsley, R. (1999). World prison populations. Home Office Research Development and Statistics Directorate, Research Findings No. 88. London: Home Office. Walmsley, R. (2003). World prison population list. Home Office Research Findings 188. Young, J. (1999). The exclusive society. London: SAGE. Zedner, L. (2002). Dangers of dystopias in penal theory. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 22, 341. David Nelken David Nelken is Distinguished Professor of Sociology at the University of Macerata, Italy, and also Distinguished Research Professor of Law at the University of Cardiff, Wales, and Honorary Professor of Law at the London School of Economics, UK. In 2007–8 he was Wiarda Chair at the Willem Pompe Institute of Criminal Law at the University of Utrecht, and in 2008–9 he will be the S.T. Lee Visiting Professor at London University’s Institute of Advanced Studies. sen4144@iperbole.bologna.it << /ASCII85EncodePages false /AllowTransparency false /AutoPositionEPSFiles true /AutoRotatePages /None /Binding /Left /CalGrayProfile (Dot Gain 20%) /CalRGBProfile (sRGB IEC61966-2.1) /CalCMYKProfile (U.S. Web Coated \050SWOP\051 v2) /sRGBProfile (sRGB IEC61966-2.1) /CannotEmbedFontPolicy /Error /CompatibilityLevel 1.4 /CompressObjects /Tags /CompressPages true /ConvertImagesToIndexed true /PassThroughJPEGImages true /CreateJDFFile false /CreateJobTicket false /DefaultRenderingIntent /Default /DetectBlends true /DetectCurves 0.0000 /ColorConversionStrategy /CMYK /DoThumbnails false /EmbedAllFonts true /EmbedOpenType false /ParseICCProfilesInComments true /EmbedJobOptions true /DSCReportingLevel 0 /EmitDSCWarnings false /EndPage -1 /ImageMemory 1048576 /LockDistillerParams false /MaxSubsetPct 100 /Optimize true /OPM 1 /ParseDSCComments true /ParseDSCCommentsForDocInfo true /PreserveCopyPage true /PreserveDICMYKValues true /PreserveEPSInfo true /PreserveFlatness true /PreserveHalftoneInfo false /PreserveOPIComments true /PreserveOverprintSettings true /StartPage 1 /SubsetFonts true /TransferFunctionInfo /Apply /UCRandBGInfo /Preserve /UsePrologue false /ColorSettingsFile () /AlwaysEmbed [ true ] /NeverEmbed [ true ] /AntiAliasColorImages false /CropColorImages true /ColorImageMinResolution 300 /ColorImageMinResolutionPolicy /OK /DownsampleColorImages true /ColorImageDownsampleType /Bicubic /ColorImageResolution 300 /ColorImageDepth -1 /ColorImageMinDownsampleDepth 1 /ColorImageDownsampleThreshold 1.50000 /EncodeColorImages true /ColorImageFilter /DCTEncode /AutoFilterColorImages true /ColorImageAutoFilterStrategy /JPEG /ColorACSImageDict << /QFactor 0.15 /HSamples [1 1 1 1] /VSamples [1 1 1 1] >> /ColorImageDict << /QFactor 0.15 /HSamples [1 1 1 1] /VSamples [1 1 1 1] >> /JPEG2000ColorACSImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 30 >> /JPEG2000ColorImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 30 >> /AntiAliasGrayImages false /CropGrayImages true /GrayImageMinResolution 300 /GrayImageMinResolutionPolicy /OK /DownsampleGrayImages true /GrayImageDownsampleType /Bicubic /GrayImageResolution 300 /GrayImageDepth -1 /GrayImageMinDownsampleDepth 2 /GrayImageDownsampleThreshold 1.50000 /EncodeGrayImages true /GrayImageFilter /DCTEncode /AutoFilterGrayImages true /GrayImageAutoFilterStrategy /JPEG /GrayACSImageDict << /QFactor 0.15 /HSamples [1 1 1 1] /VSamples [1 1 1 1] >> /GrayImageDict << /QFactor 0.15 /HSamples [1 1 1 1] /VSamples [1 1 1 1] >> /JPEG2000GrayACSImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 30 >> /JPEG2000GrayImageDict << /TileWidth 256 /TileHeight 256 /Quality 30 >> /AntiAliasMonoImages false /CropMonoImages true /MonoImageMinResolution 1200 /MonoImageMinResolutionPolicy /OK /DownsampleMonoImages true /MonoImageDownsampleType /Bicubic /MonoImageResolution 1200 /MonoImageDepth -1 /MonoImageDownsampleThreshold 1.50000 /EncodeMonoImages true /MonoImageFilter /CCITTFaxEncode /MonoImageDict << /K -1 >> /AllowPSXObjects false /CheckCompliance [ /None ] /PDFX1aCheck false /PDFX3Check false /PDFXCompliantPDFOnly false /PDFXNoTrimBoxError true /PDFXTrimBoxToMediaBoxOffset [ 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 ] /PDFXSetBleedBoxToMediaBox true /PDFXBleedBoxToTrimBoxOffset [ 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 0.00000 ] /PDFXOutputIntentProfile () /PDFXOutputConditionIdentifier () /PDFXOutputCondition () /PDFXRegistryName () /PDFXTrapped /False /Description << /CHS /CHT /DAN /DEU /ESP /FRA /ITA /JPN /KOR /NLD (Gebruik deze instellingen om Adobe PDF-documenten te maken die zijn geoptimaliseerd voor prepress-afdrukken van hoge kwaliteit. De gemaakte PDF-documenten kunnen worden geopend met Acrobat en Adobe Reader 5.0 en hoger.) /NOR /PTB /SUO /SVE /ENU (Use these settings to create Adobe PDF documents best suited for high-quality prepress printing. Created PDF documents can be opened with Acrobat and Adobe Reader 5.0 and later.) >> /Namespace [ (Adobe) (Common) (1.0) ] /OtherNamespaces [ << /AsReaderSpreads false /CropImagesToFrames true /ErrorControl /WarnAndContinue /FlattenerIgnoreSpreadOverrides false /IncludeGuidesGrids false /IncludeNonPrinting false /IncludeSlug false /Namespace [ (Adobe) (InDesign) (4.0) ] /OmitPlacedBitmaps false /OmitPlacedEPS false /OmitPlacedPDF false /SimulateOverprint /Legacy >> << /AddBleedMarks false /AddColorBars false /AddCropMarks false /AddPageInfo false /AddRegMarks false /ConvertColors /ConvertToCMYK /DestinationProfileName () /DestinationProfileSelector /DocumentCMYK /Downsample16BitImages true /FlattenerPreset << /PresetSelector /MediumResolution >> /FormElements false /GenerateStructure false /IncludeBookmarks false /IncludeHyperlinks false /IncludeInteractive false /IncludeLayers false /IncludeProfiles false /MultimediaHandling /UseObjectSettings /Namespace [ (Adobe) (CreativeSuite) (2.0) ] /PDFXOutputIntentProfileSelector /DocumentCMYK /PreserveEditing true /UntaggedCMYKHandling /LeaveUntagged /UntaggedRGBHandling /UseDocumentProfile /UseDocumentBleed false >> ] >> setdistillerparams << /HWResolution [2400 2400] /PageSize [612.000 792.000] >> setpagedevice work_jrfr25sj6vfa5ksvhgnodzhuhu ---- [PDF] Pathway to Social Justice: Research on Human Rights and Gender‐Based Violence in a Rwandan Refugee Camp | Semantic Scholar Skip to search formSkip to main content> Semantic Scholar's Logo Search Sign InCreate Free Account You are currently offline. Some features of the site may not work correctly. DOI:10.1097/ANS.0b013e3181a3b0c4 Corpus ID: 24215078Pathway to Social Justice: Research on Human Rights and Gender‐Based Violence in a Rwandan Refugee Camp @article{Pavlish2009PathwayTS, title={Pathway to Social Justice: Research on Human Rights and Gender‐Based Violence in a Rwandan Refugee Camp}, author={C. Pavlish and A. Ho}, journal={Advances in Nursing Science}, year={2009}, volume={32}, pages={144–157} } C. Pavlish, A. Ho Published 2009 Sociology, Medicine Advances in Nursing Science Gender-based violence persists in postconflict settings. Implementing an ethnographic study with Congolese refugees in Rwanda, we investigated community perspectives on justice and human rights. As core concepts, participants described the right to equal value as human beings and the corresponding responsibility to respect human rights as the basis for justice. Three factors that impede human rights include cultural ideology, social distance, and lack of a rights-enabling environment. Men… Expand View on Wolters Kluwer providencehealthcare.org Save to Library Create Alert Cite Launch Research Feed Share This Paper 14 CitationsBackground Citations 5 View All Topics from this paper Sex Characteristics 14 Citations Citation Type Citation Type All Types Cites Results Cites Methods Cites Background Has PDF Publication Type Author More Filters More Filters Filters Sort by Relevance Sort by Most Influenced Papers Sort by Citation Count Sort by Recency Health and human rights advocacy: Perspectives from a Rwandan refugee camp C. Pavlish, A. Ho, Ann-Marie Rounkle Political Science, Medicine Nursing ethics 2012 16 View 2 excerpts, cites background Save Alert Research Feed Promoting positive male gender socialization among migrant male youth living in Kakuma Refugee Camp, Kenya: Applying appreciative inquiry to gender-based violence prevention efforts M. Fry Political Science 2016 2 PDF Save Alert Research Feed Barriers of Reporting Sexual Violence in Syrian Refugee Camps E. MacTavish Medicine 2016 3 View 2 excerpts, cites background Save Alert Research Feed Understanding the Relationship Between Male Gender Socialization and Gender-Based Violence Among Refugees in Sub-Saharan Africa M. Fry, A. Skinner, S. Wheeler Psychology, Medicine Trauma, violence & abuse 2017 1 View 2 excerpts, cites background Save Alert Research Feed Measuring Distress Levels of Refugee Women to Enhance Community-Based Psycho-social Interventions Irene C Felsman, J. Humphreys, Rebecca A Kronk Psychology, Medicine Issues in mental health nursing 2019 2 View 1 excerpt, cites background Save Alert Research Feed Religion at the Margins: Resistance to Secular Humanitarianism at the Rohingya Refugee Camps in Bangladesh Nusrat Jahan Mim Political Science 2020 1 Save Alert Research Feed Accountability strategies for sexual and reproductive health and reproductive rights in humanitarian settings: a scoping review M. Schaaf, Victoria Boydell, M. Sheff, C. Kay, Fatemeh Torabi, Rajat Khosla Political Science, Medicine Conflict and Health 2020 2 PDF View 1 excerpt, cites background Save Alert Research Feed VIOLENCE AGAINST WOMEN: INTEGRATIVE REVIEW VIOLÊNCIA CONTRA A MULHER: REVISÃO INTEGRATIVA LA VIOLENCIA CONTRA LA MUJER: REVISIÓN INTEGRAL Laís de Andrade Martins Cordeiro, Samara Macedo Cordeiro, Ciderleia Castro de Lima, Telma, L. B. Franco, Clícia Valim Côrtes Gradim 2013 2 Save Alert Research Feed 'By seeing with our own eyes, it can remain in our mind': qualitative evaluation findings suggest the ability of participatory video to reduce gender-based violence in conflict-affected settings. Tilly Gurman, Regan M Trappler, A. Acosta, Pamella A McCray, C. M. Cooper, L. Goodsmith Medicine Health education research 2014 26 PDF Save Alert Research Feed Conflict, Displacement, and IPV Etobssie Wako, L. Elliott, Stacy L De Jesus, M. Zotti, M. Swahn, J. Beltrami Psychology, Medicine Violence against women 2015 12 Save Alert Research Feed ... 1 2 ... References SHOWING 1-10 OF 72 REFERENCES SORT BYRelevance Most Influenced Papers Recency Refugee Women's Health: Collaborative Inquiry with Refugee Women in Rwanda C. Pavlish Sociology, Medicine Health care for women international 2005 26 Save Alert Research Feed Gender-Based Violence in Conflict-Affected Settings: Overview of a Multi-Country Research Project J. Ward, Jessica Brewer Sociology 2004 10 Save Alert Research Feed Suffering in silence: a study of sexual and gender based violence (SGBV) in Pabbo camp Gulu district northern Uganda. Akumu Co, I. Amony, G. Otim Political Science 2005 32 PDF Save Alert Research Feed Narrative inquiry into life experiences of refugee women and men. C. Pavlish Medicine International nursing review 2007 45 Save Alert Research Feed Domestic violence and mental health: correlates and conundrums within and across cultures. R. Fischbach, B. Herbert Sociology, Medicine Social science & medicine 1997 291 PDF Save Alert Research Feed Understanding the causes of gender-based violence. Roselidah Ondeko, S. Purdin Sociology 2004 18 Save Alert Research Feed Reinvesting in social justice: a capital idea for public health nursing? D. Drevdahl, S. Kneipp, M. Canales, K. Dorcy Political Science, Medicine ANS. Advances in nursing science 2001 65 Save Alert Research Feed Toward a Critical Theoretical Interpretation of Social Justice Discourses in Nursing S. Kirkham, A. Browne Sociology, Medicine ANS. Advances in nursing science 2006 121 Save Alert Research Feed Intimate partner violence: causes and prevention R. Jewkes Psychology, Medicine The Lancet 2002 1,569 PDF Save Alert Research Feed Gender-based violence, relationship power, and risk of HIV infection in women attending antenatal clinics in South Africa K. Dunkle, R. Jewkes, H. Brown, G. Gray, S. Harlow Medicine The Lancet 2004 1,304 Save Alert Research Feed ... 1 2 3 4 5 ... Related Papers Abstract Topics 14 Citations 72 References Related Papers Stay Connected With Semantic Scholar Sign Up About Semantic Scholar Semantic Scholar is a free, AI-powered research tool for scientific literature, based at the Allen Institute for AI. Learn More → Resources DatasetsSupp.aiAPIOpen Corpus Organization About UsResearchPublishing PartnersData Partners   FAQContact Proudly built by AI2 with the help of our Collaborators Terms of Service•Privacy Policy The Allen Institute for AI By clicking accept or continuing to use the site, you agree to the terms outlined in our Privacy Policy, Terms of Service, and Dataset License ACCEPT & CONTINUE work_js7skntvnvc2lfzivm7bev3qdq ---- Forensic science: defending justice | Semantic Scholar Skip to search formSkip to main content> Semantic Scholar's Logo Search Sign InCreate Free Account You are currently offline. Some features of the site may not work correctly. DOI:10.1080/20961790.2016.1243083 Corpus ID: 53730142Forensic science: defending justice @article{Shen2016ForensicSD, title={Forensic science: defending justice}, author={M. Shen and D. N. Vieira}, journal={Forensic sciences research}, year={2016}, volume={1}, pages={1 - 2} } M. Shen, D. N. Vieira Published 2016 Political Science, Medicine Forensic sciences research Forensic science is the application of scientific knowledge and methodology for the resolution of legal questions and problems for individuals and society. It involves the observation, documentation, collection, analysis, assessment and scientific interpretation of evidence during the course of an investigation required for the different fields of law, including criminal, civil, work, family and administrative. Forensic scientists also testify as expert witnesses and can work for either the… Expand View on Taylor & Francis tandfonline.com Save to Library Create Alert Cite Launch Research Feed Share This Paper Topics from this paper Forensic Sciences Journal Forensic Medicine forensic psychiatry (field) Cessation of life Forensic Toxicology Scientific Publication Entomology Paper forensic pathology discipline Anthropology Psychiatry Specialty Forensic Genetics Drowning Pathology, Clinical Tai Ji Flexed Sidebent Rotated Cadaver Numerous Death by strangulation Lobular Neoplasia Index Periodicals Academia (organization) Promotion (action) Related Papers Abstract Topics Related Papers Stay Connected With Semantic Scholar Sign Up About Semantic Scholar Semantic Scholar is a free, AI-powered research tool for scientific literature, based at the Allen Institute for AI. Learn More → Resources DatasetsSupp.aiAPIOpen Corpus Organization About UsResearchPublishing PartnersData Partners   FAQContact Proudly built by AI2 with the help of our Collaborators Terms of Service•Privacy Policy The Allen Institute for AI By clicking accept or continuing to use the site, you agree to the terms outlined in our Privacy Policy, Terms of Service, and Dataset License ACCEPT & CONTINUE work_jvt2pmzsfvb73p2qgmcxdt7kv4 ---- Grant Writing Workshop for Environmental Justice ~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~z 7> '1F Xz77inR R i l | 01( X W;~~~~~~~~~~~ Gate met Ne enIromna jusic reeac gatee nld lf orgt ineQil CaEo Pora Kas Coo, ndMihal eliau tants, health care providers, and environ- mental health researchers. The program seeks to ensure that the communities involved have a demonstrable role in iden- tifying and defining problems and risks related to environmental health and in shaping future research approaches to such problems. The purposes of this orientation meet- ing were to share information among grantees and NIEHS staff, to allow grantees to learn of common or similar approaches in their projects, and to begin developing a communication network. Following a welcome and introduction by Anne Sassaman, director of extramural research and training, and Allen Dearry, program administrator, the principal inves- tigator of each grant described his or her project, including its history, objectives, and methods. Dianne Quigley at Clark University, in Worcester, Massachusetts, in collaboration with Native Americans for a Clean Environment and Citizen Alert Native American Program, is working to increase the awareness of Native American commu- nities exposed to radiation contamination in their environment. They are designing and implementing a plan for risk manage- ment and prevention at the Western Shoshone Nation near the Department of Energy's Nevada Test Site and at the Cherokee Nation at Sequoyah Fuels, Oklahoma, a uranium processing facility that was in operation for 23 years. Education modules of two types will be implemented: community modules, creat- ed exclusively by Native American collabo- rators; and health education modules, cre- ated by scientists and health care provider trainers. Relevant materials and strategies will be shared with other Native American communities. Katsi Cook at The State University of New York, Albany, in collaboration with St. Regis Mohawk Health Services, is designing community-based strategies for environmental health education, outreach, and training in the Akwesasne Mohawk community, which is adjacent to a Sup- erfund site in the Great Lakes Basin-St. Lawrence River watershed. Environmental hazards have resulted from the rapid transi- tion from an agricultural to an industrial environment. Cook is a nurse midwife and a member of the Mohawk community, and the project is implemented, evaluated, and disseminated explicitly through com- munity members. Michael Belliveau and Carlos Porras from Citizens for a Better Environment, in collaboration with the Labor Occupational Safety and Health Program and the Center for Occupational and Environmental Health at UCLA and the Community Health Foundation, aim to educate com- munity members and health care providers, promote adoption of pollution prevention measures, and establish a com- munity-based strategy for reducing com- munity and worker exposure to environ- mental pollutants in southeast Los Angeles, a highly industrialized area home to a low- income population, which is approximate- ly 90% Hispanic and Latino. A major objective of this project is to analyze data to confirm the list of environmental pollu- tants already known and to determine whether gaps exist in the data. Environ- mental health issues will be determined and addressed. Education of community members and medical care providers will be emphasized. Sources of health hazards will be identified, and strategies will be developed to attempt exposure reduction. Grant Writing Workshop for Environmental Justice An instructional workshop for writing a grant application in response to request for applications (RFA) ES 95-002, "Environmental Justice: Partnerships for Communication," was held at NIEHS on December 9. This RFA is a reannounce- ment of the initiative that resulted in three awards earlier this year (see previous story). At this workshop, NIEHS staff discussed the fundamentals of how to write an NIH grant application. Open to the public, the workshop attracted 30 participants, who spent the day learning about this RFA and the NIH grant process. Allen Dearry, program administrator, explained the mission of NIEHS, particu- larly as it relates to environmental justice, and then addressed this RFA specifically. The objectives, eligibility criteria, and review process were described. The three current grantees, Dianne Quigley, Katsi Cook, and Michael Belliveau, then present- ed their projects and discussed how they put together successful applications for the first round of competition. They discussed personnel interactions among community members, health care providers, and researchers, and provided the audience with some helpful hints on how to bring people together for successful collaborations. Diane Becker, director of the Center for Health Promotion at Johns Hopkins University, and a member of the Special Review Committee that evaluated the applications submitted in the first competi- tion, explained her impressions of the review process. The review committee is composed of a 1:1:1 ratio of community representatives, health care providers, and environmental health scientists. After the presentations Dearry led the group through a lesson in filling out a PHS 398, the offi- cial NIH grant application form. Carolyn Winters, grants management specialist, reviewed budgetary considerations and needed assurances and certifications. General questions and answers and individ- ual discussions rounded out the session. 140 Environmental Health Perspectives work_jwzgazhfrzdz7i74khkpjvcqde ---- European criminal justice on the move ERA Forum (2015) 16:273–276 DOI 10.1007/s12027-015-0401-4 E D I T O R I A L European criminal justice on the move Cornelia Riehle1 Published online: 16 September 2015 © ERA 2015 A major change to the area of freedom, security and justice has been seen recently, especially since the end of 2014. From the perspective of EU Justice policy, the end of 2014 marked a turning point, with the conclusion of the European Council’s five-year Stockholm Programme and the publication of the ‘EU Justice Agenda for 2020’,1 together with the new ‘Strategic Guidelines for Legislative and Operational Planning for the coming years within the EU’s Area of Freedom, Security and Justice’,2 encouraging further action on issues such as the strengthening of the rights of accused and suspected persons in criminal proceedings; the protection of victims; enhancing mutual recognition of decisions in criminal matters; reinforcing the exchange of information between the authorities of the Member States; and advancing negotiations regarding the European Public Prosecutor’s Office (EPPO). From an institutional perspective, the end of 2014 heralded the start of the period in which the Lisbon Treaty began to take full effect. As described in the Article of Dr. Els De Busser in this volume of the ERA Forum, the transitional period for the Lisbon Treaty ended on 1 December 2014, making space for new voting rules, new compe- tences of the European Commission and the CJEU, and a new position for the UK in the area of police and judicial cooperation in criminal matters in the EU. National 1EU Justice Agenda for 2020—Strengthening Trust, Mobility and Growth within the Union, COM(2014) 144 final, Strasbourg, 11.3.2014. 2Strategic Guidelines for Legislative and Operational Planning for the coming years within the EU’s Area of Freedom, Security and Justice, OJ C 240/13, 24.7.2014. B C. Riehle, M.A., Deputy Head of Section European Criminal Law criehle@era.int 1 Academy of European Law (ERA), Metzer Allee 4, 54295 Trier, Germany http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1007/s12027-015-0401-4&domain=pdf mailto:criehle@era.int 274 C. Riehle courts from all EU Member States may now look to the CJEU for the interpretation of EU law. Furthermore, the European Commission can now execute infringement procedures in the case of legal acts of police and judicial cooperation in criminal matters, which provides an exciting possibility, considering the many legal instru- ments that Member States failed to implement. Especially exciting in this regard will be the developments in the area of mutual recognition of judgements and probation decisions regarding the supervision of probation measures and alternative sanctions; alternatives to provisional detention; and judgements imposing custodial sentences or measures involving the deprivation of liberty. (Member States were supposed to take the necessary measures to comply with the three respective Framework Decisions3 by the end of 2011 but the implementation of such measures is still pending in many Member States). The European Investigation Order is a novelty in the field of mutual recognition instruments. After years of discussion and the failed establishment of the European Evidence Order (EIO), Directive 2014/41/EU4 could be adopted in April 2014, allowing a judicial authority in one Member State to request that specific crim- inal investigative measures be carried out by an authority in another Member State in order to obtain evidence. The EIO may also be issued for obtaining evidence that is already in the possession of the competent authorities of the executing State. Antonio Roma Valdés’ article in this volume of the ERA Forum outlines the problems that the principle of mutual recognition in criminal matters—once titled the ‘cornerstone’ of judicial cooperation in criminal matters in the EU—has revealed over the years. Looking at the current state of European criminal justice, another big question is posed regarding the future role of the UK in the area of freedom, security and justice. As outlined in the article of David Dickson, on 31 May 2014 the UK exercised its opt out of all EU police and criminal justice measures, and on 1 December 2014 opted back into 35 measures. Furthermore, considerable changes are also being seen currently with regard to the relevant EU Agencies in the field of police and judicial cooperation in criminal matters, namely Europol, Eurojust, and OLAF. Regarding Europol, a possible reform of its legal basis currently being discussed suggests transforming the Europol Decision into a Regulation.5 Under the draft Reg- ulation, the obligations on Member States to share law enforcement information with Europol and to initiate a criminal investigation when requested by Europol would be 3Council Framework Decision 2009/829/JHA of 23 October 2009 on the application, between Member States of the European Union, of the principle of mutual recognition to decisions on supervision measures as an alternative to provisional detention, OJ L 294/20, 11.11.2009. Council Framework Decision 2008/947/JHA on the application of the principle of mutual recognition to judgements and probation decisions with a view to the supervision of probation measures and alternative sanctions, OJ L 337/102, 16.12.2008. Council Framework Decision 2008/909/JHA of 27 November 2008 on the application of the princi- ple of mutual recognition to judgements in criminal matters imposing custodial sentences or measures involving deprivation of liberty for the purpose of their enforcement in the European Union, OJ L 327/27, 5.12.2008. 4Directive 2014/41/EU of 3 April 2014 regarding the European Investigation Order in criminal matters, OJ L 130/1, 1.5.2014. 5Proposal for a Regulation on the European Union Agency for Law Enforcement Cooperation and Training (Europol) and repealing Decisions 2009/371/JHA and 2005/681/JHA, COM(2013) 173 final, Brussels, 27.3.2013. European criminal justice on the move 275 strengthened. The draft Regulation also addresses issues of governance, the parlia- mentary scrutiny of Europol and data protection. The idea of merging the functions of Europol and the European Police College (CEPOL) into a single European Agency for Law Enforcement Cooperation and Training, as envisaged by the Commission’s original proposal in 2013, has however already been abandoned due to the opposition of the Council and European Parliament. Hence, CEPOL remains an independent EU agency, with its seat however moved from Bramshill in the UK to Budapest in Hungary. A similar discussion began with regard to Eurojust in July 2013 when the Com- mission published a proposal for a draft Regulation,6 replacing the current Eurojust Decision. The draft Regulation aims to improve the operational functions and powers of Eurojust’s National Members by, for instance, allowing them to issue and exe- cute requests and to order investigative measures in urgent cases. Furthermore, it also addresses Eurojust’s structure and governance, its data protection regime, and its cooperation with EU partners, third States and international organisations and bod- ies. A ground-breaking new development, however, is currently taking place through the discussions on the establishment of a European Public Prosecutor’s Office (EPPO). The EPPO would have a major impact on Eurojust as well as on OLAF, the European Anti-Fraud Office. The Commission’s proposal for a Regulation7 on the establishment of the EPPO was published on 17 July 2013, together with the draft Eurojust Regulation. Under the current draft of March 2015,8 the EPPO would have a collegial structure, and the EPPO and national prosecution services would have concurrent competence to investigate offences against the financial interests of the Union. Corruption cases and the problems with asset recovery in Germany are also dealt with in Dr. Markus Rübenstahl’s article in this volume of the ERA Fo- rum. In addition to all these institutional changes, European criminal law also faces new challenges with modern crime such as cybercrime and the jurisdictional prob- lems which arise. In his article in this volume of the ERA Forum, Dr. Cristos Ve- lascoanalyses the European instruments that address the issue of cybercrime juris- diction. A different perspective on policing online child sexual abuse is given by criminal psychologist Jonathan Taylor M.Sc., explaining the common characteris- tics of paedophiles. Another crime which is being comprehensively discussed at the moment is the trafficking in human beings (THB). The trends and challenges facing policy-makers regarding labour exploitation and trafficking for labour exploitation are discussed by Mariyana Radeva Berket in this volume. Furthermore, Dr. Gerrit Huybreghts describes the challenges regarding the border policy of the EU and the evolution of the Schengen zone upon its 25th anniversary. 6Proposal for a Regulation on the European Union Agency for Criminal Justice Cooperation (Eurojust), COM(2013) 535 final, Brussels, 17.7.2013. 7Proposal for a Regulation on the establishment of the European Public Prosecutor’s Office, COM(2013) 534 final, Brussels, 17.7.2013. 8Proposal for a Regulation on the establishment of the European Public Prosecutor’s Office—Orientation debate/State of Play, 6318/1/15 REV 1, 2 March 2015. 276 C. Riehle Finally, the added value of establishing criminal offences for at least serious forms of market abuse is discussed by Sarah Wilson in this volume. Finally, after a long pe- riod of disregard, the EU has also drawn its attention to the need for procedural rights. In 2009, the Swedish Presidency published a Roadmap9 for strengthening procedu- ral rights of suspected or accused persons in criminal proceedings, envisaging six measures to be taken to improve the rights of these persons in criminal proceedings, namely regarding: the right to translation and interpretation; the right to informa- tion on rights and information about the charges; legal advice and legal aid; com- munication with relatives, employers and consular authorities; special safeguards for suspected or accused persons who are vulnerable; and a Green Paper on pre-trial de- tention. Until now, the development of procedural rights has progressed steadily, with three Directives having been adopted.10 Proposals to strengthen the presumption of innocence and the right to be present at trial in criminal proceedings;11 minimum standards for legal aid in criminal proceedings,12 and the provision of protection for children and other vulnerable groups13 have all been tabled and are currently in the legislative process. It will be exciting to see what the final Directives will look like and how they will be implemented and applied in practice. 9Resolution of 30 November 2009 on a Roadmap for strengthening procedural rights of suspected or accused persons in criminal proceedings, OJ C 295/1, 4.12.2009. 10Directive 2010/64/EU on the right to interpretation and translation in criminal proceedings, OJ L 280/1, 26.10.2010; Directive 2012/13/EU on the right to information in criminal proceedings, OJ L 142/1, 1.6.2012; Directive 2013/48/EU of 22 October 2013 on the right of access to a lawyer in criminal proceedings and in European arrest warrant proceedings, and on the right to have a third party informed upon deprivation of liberty and to communicate with third persons and with consular authorities while deprived of liberty, OJ L 294/1, 6.11.2013. 11Proposal for a Directive on the strengthening of certain aspects of the presumption of innocence and of the right to be present at trial in criminal proceedings, COM(2013) 821 final, Brussels, 27.11.2013. 12Proposal for a Directive on provisional legal aid for suspects or accused persons deprived of liberty and legal aid in European arrest warrant proceedings, COM(2013) 824 final, Brussels, 27.11.2013. 13Proposal for a Directive on procedural safeguards for children suspected or accused in criminal proceed- ings, COM(2013) 822 final, Brussels, 27.11.2013. European criminal justice on the move work_jyjouu65qbeb5a6estiyvgku4i ---- doi:10.1016/j.obhdp.2005.09.001 Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 100 (2006) 110–127 www.elsevier.com/locate/obhdp Justice and personality: Using integrative theories to derive moderators of justice eVects � Jason A. Colquitt a,¤, Brent A. Scott a, Timothy A. Judge a, John C. Shaw b a University of Florida, USA b Mississippi State University, USA Received 29 July 2004 Available online 10 November 2005 Abstract Although organizational justice has been shown to have behavioral consequences, there remains a surprising amount of variation in how individuals react to fair and unfair treatment. The present study drew on three integrative theories in the justice literature— fairness heuristic theory, uncertainty management theory, and fairness theory—to identify personality traits that could explain such variation. From these theories, we identiWed trust propensity, risk aversion, and morality (rooted in circumplex models of personal- ity) as potential moderators. A laboratory study provided some support for the prediction that the three traits moderate the eVects of procedural, interpersonal, and distributive justice on task performance and counterproductive behavior. The moderating eVects of the three traits explained more variance in the outcomes than moderators based in the justice literature (equity sensitivity, sensitivity to befallen injustice) or the Wve-factor model of personality. Taken together, the results suggest that the three integrative theories can inform the search for personality-based moderators of justice eVects. © 2005 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. Keywords: Organizational justice; Fairness; Trust; Personality Fair treatment impacts an organization’s members in a number of ways. It provides evidence that organiza- tional authorities are trustworthy, reducing fears of exploitation while enhancing the legitimacy of organiza- tional actions (Lind, 2001; Tyler & Lind, 1992; Van den Bos, 2001a). Fair treatment also makes future events more predictable and controllable, reducing some of the uncertainty experienced in day-to-day working life (Lind & Van den Bos, 2002; Thibaut & Walker, 1975). Finally, fair treatment signals an adherence to moral and ethical standards on the part of authorities, potentially bringing � An earlier draft of this manuscript was presented in T.A. Judge and J.A. Colquitt (Chairs), The how and why of fairness: Mediators/modera- tors of justice eVects. Symposium conducted at the annual meeting of the Society for Industrial and Organizational Psychology, Chicago, IL. * Corresponding author. Fax: +1 352 392 6020. E-mail address: colquitt@uX.edu (J.A. Colquitt). 0749-5978/$ - see front matter © 2005 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. doi:10.1016/j.obhdp.2005.09.001 more meaning to working life (Cropanzano, Byrne, Bob- ocel, & Rupp, 2001; Folger, 1998). The members of an organization can evaluate fairness along a number of dimensions. Distributive justice refers to the perceived fairness of decision outcomes and is judged by gauging whether rewards are proportional to costs (Homans, 1961), whether outcomes adhere to expectations (Blau, 1964), and whether outcome/input ratios match those of a comparison other (Adams, 1965). Procedural justice refers to the perceived fairness of deci- sion-making procedures and is judged by gauging whether procedures are accurate, consistent, unbiased, and correctable (Leventhal, 1980), and open to employee input (Thibaut & Walker, 1975). Interactional justice refers to the perceived fairness of the enactment or implementation of procedures (Bies & Moag, 1986) and has two subfacets. Interpersonal justice captures the sin- cerity and respectfulness of authority communication, mailto: colquitt@ufl.edu mailto: colquitt@ufl.edu mailto: colquitt@ufl.edu mailto: colquitt@ufl.edu J.A. Colquitt et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 100 (2006) 110–127 111 while informational justice concerns the use of honest and adequate explanations for decisions (Colquitt, 2001; Greenberg, 1993a). These justice dimensions have been associated with a number of behavioral reactions on the part of employees (for meta-analytic reviews, see Cohen-Charash & Spec- tor, 2001; Colquitt, Conlon, Wesson, Porter, & Ng, 2001), including counterproductive behavior (Green- berg, 1990, 1993b, 2002; Skarlicki, Folger, & Tesluk, 1999) and task performance (Konovsky & Cropanzano, 1991; Van den Bos, Vermunt, & Wilke, 1996). However, meta-analytic results suggest that a substantial amount of variation exists in these relationships, and that moder- ators could explain much of that variation (Colquitt et al., 2001). Indeed, the relationships between the justice dimensions and performance are some of the most inconsistent eVects in the literature. The purpose of the present study was to identify per- sonality-based moderators that could explain some of the inconsistencies in the eVects of justice on task perfor- mance and counterproductive behavior. According to the interactional psychology perspective, behavior is determined by a complex interplay of personal and situ- ational variables such that personality alters the cogni- tive construction of an individual’s environment and shapes the meaning of the various responses to that envi- ronment (Schneider, 1983). Applied to the study of reac- tions to fair and unfair treatment, this perspective would acknowledge that personality alters individuals’ percep- tions of their treatment while also shaping the cognitive and behavioral reactions triggered by those perceptions. Thus, we focus on personality moderators of justice eVects, though both personal and situational diVerences could potentially serve as boundary conditions. If personality variables indeed are capable of explain- ing variation in justice reactions, the key question becomes which personality traits are most worthy of study. To make that critical choice, we drew on the set of theories that has been introduced in the justice literature over the past Wve years: fairness heuristic theory (Lind, 2001; Van den Bos, 2001a), uncertainty management theory (Lind & Van den Bos, 2002; Van den Bos & Lind, 2002), and fairness theory (Folger & Cropanzano, 2001). These theories represent what Colquitt, Greenberg, and Zapata-Phelan (2005) termed the “integrative wave” of the justice literature, described as “a phase in which scholars began building models and theories that exam- ined the eVects of multiple justice dimensions in combi- nation” (p. 35). The theories are termed “integrative” because, unlike other theories that focus on only one type of justice (e.g., equity theory, Adams, 1965), the integrative theories consider multiple forms of justice in concert. Because these three integrative theories capture much of the current thinking on why justice matters to people and why it impacts their behavior, we reasoned that the mechanisms in those theories could highlight potentially impactful moderators. Moreover, given that Lind (2001) suggested that the most relevant dependent variables in fairness heuristic theory are those variables that capture the distinction between cooperative and antisocial behaviors, and Folger and Cropanzano (2001) argued that fairness theory can explain the presence ver- sus absence of retaliatory behaviors, we felt that task performance and counterproductive behavior were appropriate outcomes for examining personality moder- ators of justice eVects. Past research on moderation of justice eVects Distributive justice research Concerns about individual diVerences in justice reac- tions are not new. In one of the Wrst reviews of the sub- ject, Major and Deaux (1982) stated that research on individual diVerences in justice behavior could be divided into two categories: (a) individual diVerences in reward allocation decisions, and (b) individual diVer- ences in reactions to inequity. The authors noted that the study of personality moderators of equity reactions was relatively rare. However, such work was bolstered by the introduction of equity sensitivity (Huseman, HatWeld, & Miles, 1987), a construct intended to capture sensitivity to diVerences in outcome/input ratios. Equity sensitivity can be conceptualized as a continuum ranging from “Benevolents” to “Entitleds.” Huseman et al. (1987) originally conceptualized Benevolents as individuals who prefer their outcome/input ratios to be less than a comparison other’s (underreward) and Entitleds as indi- viduals who prefer their outcome/input ratios to be greater than a comparison other’s (overreward). King, Miles, and Day (1993) redeWned Benevolents as having greater tolerance for underreward, with Entitleds having greater tolerance for overreward. In between Benevo- lents and Entitleds are “Equity Sensitives,” who adhere to Adams’s (1965) original conceptualization of equity reactions—experiencing distress when their ratios diVer in either direction. Procedural justice research Though the introduction of procedural justice pro- vided a potential new direction for research on personal- ity moderators of justice eVects, very few studies have pursued this direction. Early studies examined traits such as locus of control (Sweeney, McFarlin, & Cotton, 1991) and delay of gratiWcation (Joy & Witt, 1992) but did not explore their moderating eVects on attitudinal or behavioral reactions. However, subsequent studies have explored personality traits as moderators of both behav- ioral and attitudinal reactions to procedural justice. Sch- mitt and Dorfel (1999) found that sensitivity to befallen 112 J.A. Colquitt et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 100 (2006) 110–127 injustice (SBI) moderated the relationship between pro- cedural justice and self-reported health. Individuals high in SBI are expected to more frequently recall unjust events, become more angry about them, be more likely to be preoccupied by them, and have a stronger urge for punitivity (Schmitt, Neumann, & Montada, 1995). Other studies have drawn from various theories to identify personality moderators of procedural justice eVects such as self-esteem (Brockner et al., 1998) and exchange ideology (Witt, Kacmar, & Andrews, 2001), the latter reXecting an employee’s expectation of (and likely response to) exchange relationships with his or her organization (Eisenberger, Cotterell, & Marvel, 1987). In addition, Hagedoorn, Buunk, and van de Vliert (2002) examined the belief in a just world as a moderator of procedural and distributive justice eVects, and a recent study by Van den Bos, Maas, Waldring, and Semin (2003) found support for the moderating role of aVect intensity on emotional reactions to procedural and dis- tributive justice. Interactional justice research The introduction of interactional justice provided another new direction for research on personality mod- erators of justice eVects. We are aware of only two stud- ies that have explored moderators of such eVects. Skarlicki et al. (1999) found that the combination of low interactional justice and low distributive justice was more likely to result in retaliation when individuals were high in negative aVectivity and low in agreeableness. Heuer, Blumenthal, Douglas, and Weinblatt (1999) reported that interactional justice had a stronger eVect on fairness perceptions for high esteem individuals, a result which provided support for the relational model of justice (Tyler & Lind, 1992). Applying integrative justice theories to personality moderators of justice eVects The articles discussed in the prior section illustrate that scholars have begun to identify personality modera- tors of justice eVects. However, two points should be noted about the extant literature. First, few studies have explored justice moderators with behavioral reactions, with outcomes instead consisting of either fairness per- ceptions (e.g., Joy & Witt, 1992; Sweeney et al., 1991) or attitudinal outcomes (e.g., Schmitt & Dorfel, 1999; Witt et al., 2001). Second, studies of moderators of procedural and interactional justice eVects remain relatively rare, with more work focusing on distributive eVects. To move the literature examining personality mod- erators of justice eVects forward, we believe it would be useful to establish a more direct linkage to the cur- rent state of theorizing in the justice literature. As noted above, fairness heuristic theory, uncertainty management theory, and fairness theory capture the current thinking about organizational justice issues. With their focus on multiple justice dimensions, these theories could hold potential for identifying personal- ity moderators that cut across more than one type of justice. Creating a more direct linkage between research on moderators of justice eVects and these integrative theories could have two primary beneWts. First, the theories could be used to establish a concep- tual framework that explains how and why a given trait could alter an individual’s response to fair or unfair treatment. Second, the theories could be used to guide the critical question of which traits to examine next, given the potentially endless list of traits avail- able for study. A brief review of integrative justice theories Fairness heuristic theory Fairness heuristic theory, which grew out of earlier work on the relational model of justice (Tyler & Lind, 1992), suggests that individuals in organizations are con- tinually faced with the “fundamental social dilemma” (Lind, 2001; Van den Bos, 2001a). Although cooperating with organizational agents can lead to better outcomes in the long term, it also raises the potential of exploita- tion. To cope with that dilemma, individuals use a “fair- ness heuristic”—a psychological shortcut used to decide whether to cooperate with authorities. Lind (2001) argued that the fundamental social dilemma highlights the importance of trust, where trust is deWned as a willingness to accept vulnerability to another based on positive expectations of that person’s intentions and actions (Mayer, Davis, & Schoorman, 1995). Unfortunately, the trustworthiness of authorities can be diYcult to judge, as it depends on assessments of unobservable concepts like integrity, benevolence, and ability. In contrast, fairness perceptions depend on rela- tively more observable phenomena such as met expecta- tions (Blau, 1964), consistency of procedures (Leventhal, 1980), and respectfulness of communication (Bies & Moag, 1986). Thus, fairness heuristic theory argues that justice is used as a proxy for trust, with fair treatment signaling a trustworthy authority (Lind, 2001; Van den Bos, 2001a). The theory suggests that the fairness heuristic is formed quickly during a “judgmental phase” using whatever fairness information is Wrst gathered or is most interpretable. Once the heuristic has been formed, the theory argues that individuals will use it as a proxy for trust to guide day-to-day actions (see Van den Bos, Wilke, & Lind, 1998a, for empirical support), a period termed the “use phase” (Lind, 2001). Individuals con- tinue to employ the heuristic until a “phase shifting event,” such as a particularly important or unexpected J.A. Colquitt et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 100 (2006) 110–127 113 change at work, causes the individual to reconsider fair- ness levels and return to the judgmental phase. Uncertainty management theory In subsequent work, Lind and Van den Bos deempha- sized uncertainty about trust per se, instead focusing on more general forms of uncertainty. For example, Van den Bos (2001b) asked participants to describe the emo- tions they typically feel when they are uncertain or not in control. Results showed that justice had a stronger eVect on reactions when uncertainty was high than when uncertainty was low. Such studies led to the formal introduction of uncertainty management theory, which was cast as a successor to fairness heuristic theory (Lind & Van den Bos, 2002; Van den Bos & Lind, 2002). Uncertainty management theory recognizes that many aspects of work and family life may contain uncer- tainty. According to the theory, fairness can remove trust-related uncertainty and mitigate the discomfort associated with other forms of uncertainty—even if they have nothing to do with authorities. The authors sum- marized this key tenet as follows: “What appears to be happening is that people use fairness to manage their reactions to uncertainty, Wnding comfort in related or even unrelated fair experiencesƒ” (Lind & Van den Bos, 2002, p. 216). Fairness theory Fairness theory argues that individuals engage in counterfactual thinking to determine the fairness of a particular event and whether authorities should be blamed for that event (Folger & Cropanzano, 2001). More speciWcally, an individual makes three diVerent counterfactual determinations: would, could, and should. An individual assesses what would have happened when he or she imagines plausible alternative states of being to the current situation. An individual assesses what could have happened when he or she determines whether events were under the discretion of an authority. When an individual assesses what should have happened, he or she considers whether the authority’s behavior was mor- ally appropriate. According to the theory, individuals typically react to a decision-making event by Wrst judging whether welfare has been reduced or threatened. If individuals determine that an injury has occurred, the next question is whether the authority can be blamed. That judgment of blame depends on the presence of other feasible alternatives, as authorities cannot be blamed if they had no control over their choice of actions. Folger and Cropanzano (2001) further suggested that blame can only be placed if some ethical principal of social conduct has been violated. The characteristics of fairness theory can be distin- guished from fairness heuristic theory and uncertainty management theory on a number of levels. First, the counterfactual thinking described in fairness theory is triggered by a discrete event, whereas the fairness heuris- tic is used and maintained across a number of events. Sec- ond, the process of judging fairness is more deliberate in fairness theory, relative to the almost subconscious short- cuts described in the other two theories. Third, the mech- anisms that guide behavioral reactions are decidedly diVerent. With its emphasis on blame, fairness theory is ideally suited to explaining counterproductive reactions (Folger & Cropanzano, 2001). In contrast, fairness heu- ristic theory’s emphasis on cooperation makes it more relevant to explaining prosocial behaviors (Lind, 2001). Which traits worthy of study can be derived from the integrative theories? The integrative theories reviewed above can be used to create a conceptual framework that describes how and why a given personality trait could moderate the eVects of certain justice dimensions. Each of the theories considers three distinct questions in some form: (a) Why do individuals care about justice—what triggers justice concerns in the Wrst place? (b) How carefully and inten- sively do individuals ruminate on justice information once their concerns have been triggered? (c) What actions could individuals take once they believe that unfairness has been experienced? As summarized in Fig. 1, these three questions provide three diVerent mechanisms that could be aVected by an individual’s personality. Consider a personality trait that makes individuals more sensitive to justice, causes them to ruminate on jus- tice information more deliberately, and increases the likelihood that they will react to injustice with some action. That trait should amplify the eVects of justice on behavioral reactions, and that result should be fairly robust across contexts because it is being realized through three distinct mechanisms. Judge and Larsen (2001) used similar logic in their stimulus–organism– response (S–O–R) model of personality inXuences on job satisfaction. They argued that personality variables should have a signiWcant eVect on job satisfaction to the extent that they aVect sensitivity to environmental stim- uli, inXuence the cognitive and emotional processing of those stimuli within the organism, and heighten the like- lihood of an eventual response. The subsequent sections of this manuscript review traits, derived from the inte- grative theories, that are likely to inXuence more than one of the mechanisms shown in Fig. 1. Trust propensity Given the central role of trust in fairness heuristic the- ory (Lind, 2001; Van den Bos, 2001a), trust propensity stands out as a personality variable that could moderate justice eVects. Trust propensity is a generalized expecta- tion about the trustworthiness of others (Mayer et al., 1995), which should impact all three of the mechanisms 114 J.A. Colquitt et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 100 (2006) 110–127 in Fig. 1. Suspicious individuals should attend more to their environment when forming trust judgments, and fairness concerns should be more easily triggered as sus- picions about ability, benevolence, and integrity govern day-to-day interactions (Mayer et al., 1995). Suspicious individuals should also ruminate on fairness-relevant information more deliberately, as the use of the fairness heuristic continues until an important event causes a “phase shift” that bumps the individual back to the judgmental phase (Lind, 2001). The threshold for phase shifting should be lower for suspicious individuals given their generally wary reactions to stimuli. If so, individu- als low in trust propensity will more frequently engage in careful analysis of justice information. Finally, individuals low in trust propensity should be more likely to respond to unfair treatment with behav- ioral repercussions. Lind (2001) noted that “the fairness heuristic is an imprecise algorithm for deciding what is the best thing to do” (p. 66). Relying on the heuristic during the use phase will inevitably cause individuals to gloss over daily or weekly Xuctuations in actual fairness levels. Suspicious individuals, on the other hand, will be unlikely to gloss over such Xuctuations. Their more care- ful and frequent analysis of actual fairness levels should allow their behaviors to be based on a cognitive ledger of treatment versus contributions. Fairness heuristic theory deemphasizes the distinc- tions among the various justice dimensions, arguing that the timing and interpretability of fairness experiences is more relevant than their actual content. Nevertheless, we would argue that trust propensity will be more likely to moderate procedural and interactional justice eVects, as opposed to distributive eVects. Models in the trust litera- ture explicitly recognize procedural principles like con- sistency, bias suppression, and ethicality as forms of integrity (Mayer et al., 1995). Those same models also recognize interactional principles like respectfulness, supportiveness, and openness as forms of benevolence (Mayer et al., 1995). In contrast, distributive principles have much less presence in trust theorizing. Trust pro- pensity should therefore be more likely to impact the consideration of (and reaction to) procedural and inter- actional information because these justice dimensions tap trustworthiness issues to a greater extent. We there- fore predicted: Hypothesis 1. Propensity to trust moderates the eVects of (a) procedural justice, and (b) interactional justice, on task performance and counterproductive behavior, such that the relationships are stronger for individuals low in trust propensity and weaker for individuals high in trust propensity. Risk aversion The shift from fairness heuristic theory to uncertainty management theory supplanted trust as a central con- cern in favor of more general uncertainty. In discussing the importance of uncertainty, Lind and Van den Bos (2002) suggested that “tolerance of risk” could be an important determinant of the importance of justice (p. 215). The personality variable that most closely captures such tolerance is risk aversion. Risk aversion is an Fig. 1. Conceptual model of personality moderators of justice eVects. J.A. Colquitt et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 100 (2006) 110–127 115 individual diVerence that captures diVerential attention to stimuli in potentially risky situations, along with the tendency to react to risk with anxiety and eventual with- drawal (e.g., Cable & Judge, 1994; Maehr & Videbeck, 1968). Though risk levels are, to a large extent, driven by situational characteristics, highly risk-averse individuals view and react to those situations diVerently than less risk-averse individuals. Risk aversion should be associated with increased sensitivity to justice concerns. Because risk-averse indi- viduals react to uncertainty with more anxiety, they should pay close attention to any environmental cues that can help them manage or mitigate such uncertainty (Lind & Van den Bos, 2002). That same sense of caution should prompt risk-averse individuals to resist relying on an “imprecise algorithm” like the fairness heuristic (Lind, 2001) in favor of a careful, reasoned analysis of authority behavior. The linkage between risk aversion and the likelihood of behavioral response is less straight- forward. It seems likely that risk-averse individuals will respond to an injustice with a behavioral response that does not create a great deal of anxiety. Because risk averse individuals react to adverse stimuli with more fre- quent withdrawal (e.g., Cable & Judge, 1994; Maehr & Videbeck, 1968), passive forms of retaliation (like decreased eVort or task performance) could be likely. Individuals’ likelihood of engaging in more active retali- ation (like counterproductive behavior) should depend on the risk involved in such acts. When the risk involved is low, counterproductive behavior should provide another means of retaliation for risk-averse individuals. Our predictions for trust propensity were limited to procedural and interactional justice because of their spe- cial relevance to trust—does the same type of distinction need to be made for risk aversion? Van den Bos and Lind (2002) deWned uncertainty quite broadly, framing it as the unpredictability of future events that deprives one of con- Wdence about what to expect from the environment. Unfair procedures should create an especially high level of uncertainty because procedures have a systemic char- acter—they remain in place over the long-term (Sweeney & McFarlin, 1993). Unfair treatment by an authority Wgure also has long-term implications on uncertainty, so long as the authority remains in his or her position for an extended period of time. In contrast, concerns about unfair outcome distributions are more short-term in ori- entation, as outcomes tend to have a discrete, episodic character. Nevertheless, distributive unfairness deprives an individual of conWdence in how to behave and what to expect. UnfulWlled expectations (Blau, 1964), inconsistent social comparisons (Adams, 1965), and divergence in rewards and costs (Homans, 1961) prevent the develop- ment of the behavior-outcome contingencies that are endemic to so many models of volitional behavior (Kan- fer, 1991). We therefore made risk aversion moderation predictions for all three justice dimensions: Hypothesis 2. Risk aversion moderates the eVects of (a) procedural justice, (b) interactional justice, and (c) dis- tributive justice on task performance and counterpro- ductive behavior, such that the relationships are stronger for individuals high in risk aversion and weaker for indi- viduals low in risk aversion. Morality In the years since fairness theory was Wrst introduced, a great deal of attention has focused on the should com- ponent of the theory, which captures whether an author- ity’s actions have complied with moral or ethical principles. This attention can be seen in the “moral vir- tue” and “deontic” perspectives on justice, which argue that justice is valued because it signiWes adherence to prevailing moral standards (Cropanzano et al., 2001; Folger, 1998, 2001; Folger, Cropanzano, & Goldman, 2005). The “deontic” term comes from the Greek word deon, meaning duty or obligation (Folger, 2001). Folger et al. (2005) argued that violations of moral principles can trigger “deontic anger,” which may prompt retalia- tory behaviors even when such actions are not rational (Folger et al., 2005). Of course, there are likely to be individual diVerences in the degree to which individuals experience deontic anger, as well as their responses to such violations. Fol- ger (1998) hinted that an individual’s morality might be one variable that captures such variation. Within the personality literature, trait morality can be operationally deWned as a combination of high agreeableness and high conscientiousness. Hofstee, de Raad, and Goldberg (1992) introduced an integration of the Big Five and cir- cumplex approaches to trait structure. The authors described 10 diVerent circumplex models, each of which illustrates various combinations (or blends) of two Big Five factors. Taken together, these 10 circumplex models were used to provide operational deWnitions for 540 spe- ciWc traits. One of those traits was “moral”, which was positioned in the high agreeableness, high conscientious- ness area of one of the circumplex models (see also de Raad, Hendriks, & Hofstee, 1992). Other studies have similarly shown that trait morality, and related concepts such as trait integrity, seem to represent a blend of high agreeableness and high conscientiousness (Ones, 1994; Saucier & Goldberg, 1996). The circumplex origin of trait morality is important in that the intersection of agreeableness and conscien- tiousness is believed to capture a behavior pattern not explainable by simple additive eVects of those two Big Five dimensions. However, we should acknowledge that this trait-based version of morality diVers from Kohl- berg’s (1984) conceptualization of the stages of moral development. A trait-based view emphasizes static or cross-sectional diVerences in morality across individuals, whereas Kohlberg’s (1984) emphasis was on within-indi- vidual transitions over time (Walker, 2002). To highlight 116 J.A. Colquitt et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 100 (2006) 110–127 this critical diVerence and reduce potential confusion, our manuscript intentionally uses the term ‘‘trait moral- ity” when describing our moderator variable. High levels of trait morality should be associated with increased sensitivity to justice concerns. From a moral virtue perspective, justice can help bring meaning to working life (Cropanzano et al., 2001; Folger, 1998). Highly moral individuals may be more likely to search for that meaning and should also be less likely to engage in unjust behaviors themselves. They should therefore react to others’ instances of injustice with more deontic anger, leading to more deliberate rumination on justice- relevant information. In a fairness theory sense, moral individuals should have a heightened interest in the should counterfactual portion of the blame assessment process (Folger & Cropanzano, 2001). The linkage between trait morality and the likelihood of behavioral response would seem to depend on the nature of the speciWc reaction. On the one hand, highly moral individuals are particularly likely to hold others responsible for their actions, as morality is associated with a tendency to ascribe responsibility (Zuckerman & Reis, 1978) and sanctions often follow from ascriptions of blame (Pizarro, Uhlmann, & Bloom, 2003). Moreover, Folger et al. (2005) suggested that retribution against the source of an injustice is itself a “moral remedy” that is consistent with social exchange theories of interaction (Blau, 1964). Bies and Tripp (1995) went so far as to describe revenge as a “moral imperative,” noting that perpetrators of revenge often report a strong belief that they were “doing the right thing” (pp. 258–259). On the other hand, individuals high in trait morality should be very resistant to the prospect of engaging in counterproductive behaviors like theft or retaliation. Indi- rect support for this assertion can be drawn from a series of studies by Turillo, Folger, Lavelle, Umphress, and Gee (2002). The studies gave participants the opportunity to either self-sacriWcially punish an individual who had exhibited unfair intentions in a past phase of the study, or self-sacriWcially reward an individual who had exhibited fair intentions. Punishments and rewards occurred using a payout matrix, where participants chose their own payout while also allocating payouts to others. Importantly, the results of one of the studies revealed that participants decided to punish past transgressions only when those actions did not harm the payouts received by other cur- rent participants. The authors wrote, “These results sup- port our reasoning that individuals will only engage in retributive justice to punish unfairness in the past when, by doing so, they are not themselves being unfair in the present.” (p. 852). Because a counterproductive response means “being unfair in the present,” a moral individual should be more likely to respond to injustice with less task-related eVort as opposed to more overt forms of retaliation. A reduction in performance can amount to a brand of “civil disobedience” that is relatively harmless to others. As a result, our hypotheses for trait morality are limited to task performance. As with the other integrative theories, fairness theory emphasizes the commonalities among the diVerent forms of justice rather than the diVerences. For example, the would counterfactual considers an event’s aversiveness, with no particular importance given to whether the event is distributive, procedural, or interactional in nature (Folger & Cropanzano, 2001). The could counter- factual assesses whether other sequences of events or actions might have been feasible, again with little emphasis on modalities of justice. However, discussions of the should counterfactual and writings on the moral virtue and deontic approaches to justice do seem to pri- oritize procedural and interactional justice violations (Folger, 1998, 2001; Folger & Cropanzano, 2001). Proce- dural and interactional justice rules, such as bias, ethical- ity, respectfulness, and honesty seem more “morally charged” than distributive concepts like met expecta- tions, reward-cost proportionality, and outcome/input ratio comparisons. Indeed, in Folger’s (2001) “deontic diVerentiation” of distributive, procedural, and interac- tional justice (pp. 22–25), he speculated that moral accountability for justice tends to grow stronger in ascending order from distributive to procedural to inter- actional (see also Turillo et al., 2002). We therefore made moderation predictions for only the latter two dimen- sions of justice: Hypothesis 3. Trait morality moderates the eVects of (a) procedural justice and (b) interactional justice on task performance, such that the relationships are stronger for individuals high in trait morality and weaker for individ- uals low in trait morality. Alternative approaches to moderation of justice eVects Though the hypotheses advanced in Fig. 1 are derived from the three theories that form the core of the so-called “integrative wave” of the justice literature (Colquitt et al., 2005), there are other potential approaches to the study of moderation of justice eVects that have been used in past research. One approach is the study of personality traits that are speciWcally designed to moderate justice eVects, as in the cases of equity sensitivity (Huseman et al., 1987) and sensitivity to befallen injustice (SBI; Sch- mitt et al., 1995). Both traits might have moderating potential, though research on equity sensitivity is limited to distributive justice eVects and research on SBI has yet to extend beyond the tests by Schmitt and colleagues (e.g., Schmitt & Dorfel, 1999; Schmitt et al., 1995). We therefore included equity sensitivity and SBI so that their moderating eVects could be compared to the eVects of trust propensity, risk aversion, and trait morality. A second alternative approach to moderation of jus- tice eVects is the Wve-factor model of personality J.A. Colquitt et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 100 (2006) 110–127 117 (Costa & McCrae, 1992; Goldberg, 1990). The “Big Five” dimensions of conscientiousness, agreeableness, neuroticism, openness to experience, and extraversion subsume many of the narrow traits shown in Fig. 1. The Big Five may also moderate justice eVects, as research by Skarlicki et al. (1999) showed that agreeableness and neuroticism moderated the eVects of speciWc justice com- binations. However, as Hogan and Roberts (1996) noted, broad traits are not always best suited for narrow predictions, and the reaction to an injustice is clearly a more speciWc criterion relative to day-to-day job perfor- mance. Nevertheless, we also included the Big Five as alternative moderators of justice eVects to provide a sec- ond frame of comparison for the eVects predicted in Fig. 1. Method Sample Participants were 238 undergraduates from a large, southeastern university recruited from an introductory management course. Females composed 45% of the sam- ple. In exchange for participation, participants were given course credit and earned a $5 cash prize. Procedure Upon entering the laboratory, participants were seated at one of Wve tables. Each table had a pen holder containing seven expensive-looking pens. The tables were arranged so that participants’ views of one another were obstructed during the session. The experimenter provided a cover story, informing participants that the purpose of the study was to validate assessment tools that would be used in the future hiring of research assis- tants. Included in these assessment tools were a proof- reading task and a reading comprehension task, and participants were told that their performance on the Wrst of these (the proofreading task) would determine whether they would receive a $5 cash prize. Participants were told that around 66% of the participants would perform well enough to receive the cash prize. This instruction ensured that all participants began the exper- iment with the same expectations for being rewarded. Participants were then told that they could choose a pen to use during the study and that they could keep the pen they chose. They were then given seven minutes to complete the proofreading task, which contained a pas- sage describing various types of work groups (e.g., for- mal, informal, virtual). Next, the experimenter informed participants that he would leave the room to grade the tasks and then would return to give the participants feedback on their performance. During the grading period, participants completed a questionnaire assessing the Big Five, risk aversion, trust, and equity sensitivity, which contained the following instructions: “This ques- tionnaire assesses various aspects of your personal and general attitudes. Please answer the questions in each section as honestly as you can.” Unless otherwise noted, all items on all questionnaires utilized a 5-point scale, where 1 D Strongly Disagree and 5 D Strongly Agree. After 10 min, the experimenter called each partici- pant individually to another room to deliver the justice manipulations. Procedural, distributive, and interac- tional justice were then manipulated by the experi- menter via eight possible statements, resulting in a 2 £ 2 £ 2 between-subjects design with participants randomly assigned to conditions. Table 1 provides the exact wording of the justice manipulations. The proce- dural manipulation varied Leventhal’s (1980) accuracy and consistency criteria for justice in a manner similar to Van den Bos, Bruins, Wilke, and Dronkert (1999). Interactional justice was manipulated using the inter- personal justice subfacet, which captures the sincerity and respectfulness of authority communication (Col- quitt, 2001; Greenberg, 1993a). The remainder of this manuscript uses the interpersonal justice label in the interest of precision. SpeciWcally, the manipulation var- Table 1 Summary of justice manipulations Justice dimension Level Text of manipulation Procedural High In the past, I’ve always graded the whole proofreading task in order to be as accurate and consistent as possible. So I took the time to carefully grade all the paragraphs that you corrected. Low In the past, I’ve always graded the whole proofreading task in order to be as accurate and consistent as possible. I didn’t do that here though. I Wnished grading everyone else’s but ran out of time on yours, so I just graded the last paragraph. Interpersonal High I understand that students are very busy, and there’s a lot of other things you could be doing right now besides helping us out. We really appreciate your time. Thanks a lot. Low Whatever. I don’t give a damn whether you get paid or not. That’s the way it is. I’ve got better things to do than grade these things. Distributive High Anyway, (from that one paragraph/based on those paragraphs) I have determined that you should be paid. Low Anyway, (from that one paragraph/based on those paragraphs) I have determined that you should not be paid. 118 J.A. Colquitt et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 100 (2006) 110–127 ied the respect and rudeness components of the con- struct (Bies & Moag, 1986). Distributive justice was manipulated by meeting or not meeting participants’ expectations about the receipt of the $5 reward, similar to the approach used by Greenberg (1993b) and Van den Bos, Wilke, Lind, and Vermunt (1998b). Partici- pants were either paid immediately, thereby meeting expectations, or were told they would not be paid, thereby failing to meet expectations. Next, participants were given 10 min to complete a reading comprehension test, which served as the measure of task performance. This test consisted of a short pas- sage describing carpal tunnel syndrome followed by eight questions which required participants to examine the speciWc details and main points of the passage to obtain the correct answers. Using reading comprehen- sion as a measure of task performance is appropriate in this context because the test was designed to be largely eVort-driven as opposed to ability-driven. The questions were not diYcult but did require a careful perusal of the passage on the part of the participant. SpeciWcally, we included a brief paragraph at the end of the passage that corrected previous statements. To answer the questions correctly, participants had to take the time to carefully read the entire passage. Participants then completed a Wnal questionnaire that contained items for the manipu- lation checks, sensitivity to befallen injustice, and trait morality. Near completion of the Wnal questionnaire, the experi- menter interrupted and stated: “Um, I have to make a phone call. When you guys are done just leave your ques- tionnaire on your desk and you’re free to go. Oh, also: I know I read from the script earlier that you could keep the pen, but we’re running some more sessions and it looks like we’re getting a little low. So, if you would not keep the pen I’d appreciate it.” The experimenter then left the room, giving participants the opportunity to take pens from the pen holder. The set up of the room prevented participants from being able to access the pen containers of others, so they could only take pens from their individ- ual pen holder. When participants exited the room, the experimenter asked each one to wait for the others. Once all had exited, the experimenter then brought the partici- pants into another room to debrief them about the true nature of the experiment. Finally, participants who did not receive the $5 during the study were paid. Integrative theory traits Trust propensity We measured trust propensity using 5 items from the International Personality Item Pool (2001). The items included: “I trust others,” “I trust what people say,” “I am wary of others (R),” “I suspect hidden motives in others (R),” and “I distrust people (R).” CoeYcient � for this scale was .81. Risk aversion Risk aversion was also assessed using 6 items from the International Personality Item Pool (2001). Items included: “I enjoy being reckless (R),” “I take risks (R),” “I seek danger (R),” “I seek adventure (R),” I would never go hang-gliding or bungee jumping,” and “I would never make a high risk investment.” CoeYcient � for this scale was .82. Trait morality This trait was measured using 6 items from the Inter- national Personality Item Pool (2001). The items included: “I would never cheat on my taxes,” “I turn my back on others (R),” I scheme against others (R),” “I act at the expense of others (R),” “I respect the privacy of others,” and “I respect authority.” CoeYcient � for this scale was .86. ConWrmatory factor analysis We conducted a conWrmatory factor analysis on the measures of the three integrative theory traits to deter- mine whether the items seemed to be tapping three dis- tinct constructs. We included a reverse-wording factor with loadings on the items worded in the opposite direc- tion from the majority of the scale, given that responses to these sorts of items can be inXuenced by careless respondents (Schmitt & Stults, 1985). The trait morality scale was balanced in wording, so the items reXecting a lack of morality were loaded onto the wording factor. We also allowed the errors for the two “I trustƒ” items to covary as their item similarity resulted in an observed correlation signiWcantly higher than the model repro- duced correlation. The results of a three-factor model provided an acceptable Wt to the data (�2 (108) D 174.50; CFI D .954; RMR D .048; RMSEA D .052). The loadings for the three personality factors were all statistically sig- niWcant and averaged as follows: trust propensity (.62), risk aversion (.63), and trait morality (.59). The correla- tions among the three latent variables were moderate in magnitude, with an absolute average of .25. Taken together, these results support the assertion that the scales are measuring three distinct factors. Alternative moderators Equity sensitivity We measured equity sensitivity using the 5-item scale developed by King and Miles (1994). Participants were asked to divide 10 points between two opposing state- ments by “giving the most points to the choice that is most like you and the fewest points to the choice that is least like you.” All Wve items began with the phrase “In any organization I might work for:” An example item is “It would be more important for me to (A) get from the organization or (B) give to the organization.” The instrument was scored by adding items reXecting J.A. Colquitt et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 100 (2006) 110–127 119 Entitledness; thus high scores represent a high sensitivity to perceived underreward. The potential range of scores was zero to 50. CoeYcient � for this scale was .77. Sensitivity to Befallen injustice We measured SBI using the 10-item scale developed by Schmitt and Maes (2000). A sample item is: “It both- ers me when others receive something that ought to be mine.” CoeYcient � for this scale was .87. Big Five dimensions We measured the Wve-factor model using the Big Five Inventory (BFI; John, Donahue, & Kentle, 1991), with dimensions as follows: neuroticism (eight items, e.g., “I can be moody,” � D .86), extraversion (eight items, e.g., “I have an assertive personality,” � D .89), openness to experience (10 items, e.g., “I am curious about many things,” � D .86), agreeableness (nine items, e.g., “I have a forgiving nature,” � D .75), and conscientiousness (eight items, e.g., “I do a thorough job,” � D .80). Outcome measures Task performance Task performance was assessed by scoring each par- ticipant’s answers to the reading comprehension test. Task performance ranged from a possible score of zero (no correct answers) to eight (all answers correct). Counterproductive behavior We measured counterproductive behavior by the number of pens taken from each participant’s pen holder upon leaving the experiment (pen holders held seven pens in total). Counterproductive behavior ranged from 0 (no pens taken) to 3 (the maximum number of pens taken by a participant). The act of tak- ing a pen when asked not to do so likely taps two diVerent counterproductive behaviors that range in severity. At its most severe, taking a pen represents a form of theft. At its least severe, taking a pen repre- sents a form of intentional noncompliance with an authority Wgure. Manipulation checks We assessed whether participants perceived the jus- tice manipulations as intended using three items for each dimension of organizational justice. The procedural jus- tice items included “The grading procedures used on the proofreading task seemed accurate.” (� D .94). The inter- personal justice items included “The experimenter spoke to me with sincerity and respect.” (� D .97). The distribu- tive justice items included “I received the $5 reward for the proofreading task.” (� D .96). We also veriWed that the manipulations aVected perceptions of fairness by including the following four-item global fairness percep- tions scale (e.g., “In general, this was a fair experiment”) (� D .96). Results Manipulation checks A MANOVA with the three manipulation check scales as dependent variables revealed signiWcant main eVects for all three manipulations (F D 903.40, p < .001, for distributive justice; F D 36.24, p < .001, for interper- sonal justice; F D 10.10, p < .001, for procedural justice) with no interaction eVects. ANOVA results showed that the distributive manipulation had a strong eVect on the distributive check (F D 2724.93, p < .001, �2 D .92, M D 4.67 vs. 1.21) and weaker eVects on the procedural (F D 20.85, p < .001, �2 D .08, M D 3.17 vs. 2.50) and inter- personal checks (F D 23.03, p < .001, �2 D .09, M D 3.99 vs. 3.33). The interpersonal manipulation had a strong eVect on the interpersonal check (F D 92.65, p < .001, �2 D .29, M D 4.25 vs. 2.84), a weaker eVect on the procedural check (F D 6.13, p < .01, �2 D .03, M D 2.99 vs. 2.58), and no eVect on the distributive check (F D .12, p D .73, �2 D .00, M D 2.77 vs. 2.85). The procedural manipulation had a strong eVect on the procedural check (F D 30.56, p < .001, �2 D .12, M D 3.20 vs. 2.36), a weaker eVect on the interpersonal check (F D 10.42, p < .001, �2 D .04, M D 3.89 vs. 3.33), and no eVect on the distributive check (F D .40, p D .53, �2 D .00, M D 2.84 vs. 2.76). All three manipulations also inXuenced global perceptions of fair- ness, explaining a total of 17% of the variance (F D 16.07, p < .001). Unique eVects were as follows: distributive jus- tice (B D .67, p < .001), procedural justice (B D .28, p < .05), and interpersonal justice (B D .54, p < .001). The ANOVA results above indicate some spillover, with a manipulation of one form of justice aVecting checks of another, which is likely due to attempting orthogonal manipulations of variables that are so highly correlated on a perceptual level (Cohen-Charash & Spector, 2001; Colquitt et al., 2001). However, the degree of spillover does not seem serious enough to impair an unambiguous evaluation of the experiment’s results (Perdue & Summers, 1986). The F values for the intended eVects were 53 times stronger than the F values for the unintended eVects, and the �2 values for the intended eVects were 12 times stronger than �2 values for the unintended eVects. Nevertheless, we statistically con- trolled for all spillover by partialling out the contaminat- ing variance from each justice manipulation. For example, we partialled out the shared variance between the procedural manipulation and the interpersonal check by regressing the latter onto the former and using the residual as the new procedural manipulation vari- able. This process resulted in a completely “clean” set of ANOVA results. We should emphasize that this form of 120 J.A. Colquitt et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 100 (2006) 110–127 statistical control did not alter the tests of any of our hypotheses but is presented here to provide as clear a picture of our results as possible. Results for integrative theory traits Table 2 provides the descriptive statistics and zero- order correlations among the variables. The moderated regressions used to test our hypotheses are shown in Table 3. The Wrst two steps assess the main and interac- tive eVects of the justice manipulations, which did not have main or interactive eVects on task performance, with the main eVects falling within the conWdence inter- vals from Colquitt et al.’s (2001) meta-analytic review. The justice manipulations did have signiWcant main and interactive eVects on counterproductive behavior, con- sistent with past research (Greenberg, 1990, 1993b, 2002), with the procedural and distributive manipula- tions reducing counterproductive behavior (though the latter eVect only approached signiWcance at p < .07). The interaction eVects showed that the combination of low procedural justice and either low interpersonal or low distributive justice created particularly high counterpro- ductive behavior levels. The third step of the regressions assesses the main eVects of the three personality traits, with none reaching statistical signiWcance. The fourth step of the regressions enters the justice £ personality product terms used to test the hypotheses. Consistent with the recommendations of Cohen, Cohen, West, and Aiken (2003), we mean-cen- tered all moderators before computing the product terms. The set of justice £ personality product terms explained signiWcant incremental variance in both task performance and counterproductive behavior. Hypothe- sis 1a and b predicted stronger eVects for procedural and interpersonal justice on task performance and counter- productive behavior when trust propensity was low. The interpersonal justice £ trust propensity interaction approached signiWcance for task performance, with the pattern in the predicted direction (p < .07, see Fig. 2). Though not predicted, the results also revealed a similar interaction with distributive justice for task performance (p < .06, see Fig. 2). A signiWcant interpersonal justice £ trust propensity interaction was also observed for counterproductive behavior, but was opposite to Table 3 Moderated regression results for trust propensity, risk aversion, and trait morality Note. n D 238. �R2 values may not sum exactly to R2 values due to rounding error. ¤ p < .05, two-tailed. ¤¤ p < .10, two-tailed. Regression step Task performance Counterproductive behavior R2 �R2 � R2 �R2 � 1. Procedural Justice (PJ) .00 .00 .05 .05¤ .05¤ ¡.19¤ Interpersonal Justice (IJ) .02 ¡.08 Distributive Justice (DJ) .00 ¡.12¤¤ 2. PJ £ IJ .01 .01 ¡.05 .10¤ .06¤ .20¤ PJ £ DJ ¡.04 .15¤ IJ £ DJ ¡.09 .07 3. Trust Propensity .03 .02 .00 .11¤ .01 ¡.02 Risk Aversion .11 .04 Trait Morality ¡.10 ¡.06 4. PJ £ Trust Propensity .12¤ .09¤ ¡.01 .23¤ .12¤ ¡.11 IJ £ Trust Propensity ¡.14¤¤ ¡.21¤ DJ £ Trust Propensity ¡.14¤¤ ¡.05 PJ £ Risk Aversion .14¤ ¡.22¤ IJ £ Risk Aversion ¡.05 ¡.19¤ DJ £ Risk Aversion ¡.06 ¡.08 PJ £ Trait Morality ¡.11 .11 IJ £ Trait Morality .25¤ ¡.02 DJ £ Trait Morality .24¤ ¡.00 Table 2 Descriptive statistics and zero-order correlations Note. n D 237. SBI D Sensitivity to Befallen Injustice. ¤ p < .05, two-tailed. Variable M SD 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 1. Procedural Justice .00 .49 — 2. Interpersonal Justice .00 .49 ¡.09 — 3. Distributive Justice .00 .48 ¡.08 ¡.12 — 4. Trust Propensity 3.79 .54 .05 .01 ¡.05 — 5. Risk Aversion 3.08 .66 ¡.00 .12 .08 .09 — 6. Trait Morality 4.15 .46 .04 .10 .00 .47¤ .40¤ — 7. Equity Sensitivity 22.45 6.12 ¡.06 .07 .04 ¡.23¤ .08 ¡.22¤ — 8. SBI 2.92 .65 .11 ¡.01 .06 ¡.32¤ .07 ¡.21¤ .19¤ — 9. Conscientiousness 4.04 .53 ¡.03 .02 ¡.03 .35¤ .09 .40¤ ¡.28¤ ¡.12 — 10. Agreeableness 3.84 .50 ¡.05 .06 ¡.03 .51¤ .12 .43¤ ¡.24¤ ¡.28¤ .28¤ — 11. Neuroticism 2.80 .73 .08 ¡.05 ¡.03 ¡.45¤ .17¤ ¡.17¤ .11 .39¤ ¡.33¤ ¡.34¤ — 12. Openness 3.64 .67 ¡.08 .07 ¡.08 .16¤ ¡.10 .17¤ ¡.12 ¡.14¤ .21¤ .23¤ ¡.13¤ — 13. Extraversion 3.58 .72 ¡.01 ¡.10 ¡.01 .41¤ ¡.10 .14¤ ¡.14¤ ¡.05 .20¤ .22¤ .24¤ .13¤ — 14. Task Performance 6.17 1.42 .05 .01 ¡.00 .03 .05 ¡.05 .09 ¡.04 .07 .08 ¡.14 .10 .03 — 15. Counterproductive Behavior .10 .30 ¡.18¤ ¡.05 ¡.10 ¡.03 ¡.04 ¡.10 .06 .07 ¡.12 ¡.02 .03 ¡.01 ¡.08 ¡.01 J.A. Colquitt et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 100 (2006) 110–127 121 predictions. The eVect of interpersonal justice on coun- terproductive behavior was stronger for trusting individ- uals. Neither of the procedural justice interactions reached statistical signiWcance. Fig. 2. Justice £ trust propensity interactions for task performance and counterproductive behavior. High Trust Propensity Low Trust Propensity High Trust Propensity Low Trust Propensity High Trust Propensity Interpersonal Justice Interpersonal Justice T a s k P e rf o rm a n c e T a s k P e rf o rm a n c e C o u n te r p ro d u c ti v e B e h a v io u r Distributive Justice Low Trust Propensity High Low High Low High Low 7.75 7.00 6.25 5.50 4.75 7.75 7.00 6.25 5.50 4.75 0.40 0.30 0.20 0.10 0.00 Hypothesis 2a–c predicted stronger eVects for proce- dural, interpersonal, and distributive justice on task per- formance and counterproductive behavior when risk aversion was high. The procedural justice £ risk aversion interaction was signiWcant for both task performance and counterproductive behavior, with the patterns in the predicted direction (see Fig. 3). A signiWcant interper- sonal justice £ risk aversion interaction was also observed for counterproductive behavior, again in the predicted direction (see Fig. 3). In all three cases, the beneWcial eVects of fair treatment were stronger for indi- Fig. 3. Justice £ risk aversion interactions for task performance and counterproductive behavior. High Risk Aversion Low Risk Aversion High Risk Aversion Low Risk Aversion High Risk Aversion Low Risk Aversion High Low High Low High Low 7.75 7.00 6.25 5.50 4.75 0.40 0.30 0.20 0.10 0.00 0.40 0.30 0.20 0.10 0.00 Interpersonal Justice Procedural Justice Procedural Justice T a s k P e rf o rm a n c e C o u n te r p ro d u c ti v e B e h a v io u r C o u n te r p ro d u c ti v e B e h a v io u r 122 J.A. Colquitt et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 100 (2006) 110–127 viduals who were highly risk-averse. Contrary to predic- tions, neither of the distributive justice interactions was signiWcant. Hypothesis 3a and b predicted stronger eVects for procedural and interpersonal justice on task perfor- mance when trait morality was high. The interpersonal justice £ trait morality interaction was signiWcant for task performance, with the pattern in the predicted direction (see Fig. 4). Though not predicted, the results also revealed a similar interaction with distributive jus- tice for task performance (see Fig. 4). In both cases, the eVects of fair treatment on task performance were more positive for individuals high in trait morality. Contrary to predictions, the procedural justice interaction was not statistically signiWcant. Results for alternative approaches to moderation of justice eVects Table 4 provides the moderated regression results for equity sensitivity and SBI. The Wrst two steps reproduce the justice manipulation results from Table 3. The third step examines the main eVects of the two traits, and nei- ther had signiWcant eVects. The fourth step examines the justice £ personality product terms, and the step was not Fig. 4. Justice £ trait morality interactions for task performance. Table 4 Moderated regression results for equity sensitivity and sensitivity to Befallen Injustice Note. n D 238. �R2 values may not sum exactly to R2 values due to rounding error. ¤ p < .05, two-tailed. ¤¤ p < .10, two-tailed. Regression step Task performance Counterproductive behavior R2 �R2 � R2 �R2 � 1. Procedural Justice (PJ) .00 .00 .05 .05¤ .05¤ ¡.19¤ Interpersonal Justice (IJ) .02 ¡.08 Distributive Justice (DJ) .00 ¡.12¤¤ 2. PJ £ IJ .01 .01 ¡.05 .10¤ .06¤ .20¤ PJ £ DJ ¡.04 .15¤ IJ £ DJ ¡.09 .07 3. Equity Sensitivity .03 .02 .11 .12¤ .01 .04 SBI ¡.08 .11 4. PJ £ Equity Sensitivity .05 .02 ¡.01 .15 .03 ¡.13 IJ £ Equity Sensitivity .10 .06 DJ £ Equity Sensitivity ¡.01 ¡.07 PJ £ SBI ¡.06 ¡.06 IJ £ SBI ¡.08 .02 DJ £ SBI ¡.09 ¡.01 Table 5 Moderated regression results for Big Five dimensions Note. n D 238. �R2 values may not sum exactly to R2 values due to rounding error. ¤ p < .05, two-tailed. ¤¤ p < .10, two-tailed. Regression step Task performance Counterproductive behavior R2 �R2 � R2 �R2 � 1. Procedural Justice (PJ) .00 .00 .05 .05¤ .05¤ ¡.19¤ Interpersonal Justice (IJ) .02 ¡.08 Distributive Justice (DJ) .00 ¡.12¤¤ 2. PJ £ IJ .01 .01 ¡.05 .10¤ .06¤ .20¤ PJ £ DJ ¡.04 .15¤ IJ £ DJ ¡.09 .07 3. Conscientiousness .04 .03 .01 .13¤ .02 ¡.12 Agreeableness .02 .01 Neuroticism ¡.15 .01 Openness .08 ¡.01 Extraversion ¡.02 ¡.08 4. PJ £ Conscientiousness .10 .06 .00 .20¤ .07 .05 IJ £ Conscientiousness .00 ¡.10 DJ£ Conscientiousness ¡.03 .04 PJ £ Agreeableness ¡.07 ¡.13 IJ £ Agreeableness ¡.15 ¡.18 DJ £ Agreeableness .04 ¡.09 PJ £ Neuroticism .04 .00 IJ £ Neuroticism ¡.03 ¡.04 DJ £ Neuroticism ¡.06 ¡.10 PJ £ Openness ¡.00 .06 IJ £ Openness .18 .05 DJ £ Openness .01 .02 PJ £ Extraversion .05 .10 IJ £ Extraversion ¡.04 .02 DJ £ Extraversion .02 .07 J.A. Colquitt et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 100 (2006) 110–127 123 signiWcant for either task performance or counterpro- ductive behavior. Table 5 presents the moderated regres- sion results for the Wve-factor model. As with the other personality traits, the third step of the regressions revealed no main eVects of the Big Five dimensions on task performance or counterproductive behavior. The fourth step examines the justice £ personality product terms, and the step was not signiWcant for either task performance or counterproductive behavior. Discussion Taken together, our results illustrate that the integra- tive theories that have emerged within the justice litera- ture over the past Wve years can be fruitful sources of potential moderators of justice eVects. Although fairness heuristic theory, uncertainty management theory, and fairness theory were not created for the express purpose of identifying personality moderators, the traits exam- ined here Xow neatly from the core propositions of each theory. The signiWcant interactions for trust propensity, risk aversion, and trait morality were observed across types of justice, supporting the replicability of the eVects. With the exception of trait morality, the interactions were also observed for both task performance and coun- terproductive behavior. The task performance eVects are notable, as the interactions help to clarify the inconsis- tent results in past studies of justice and performance (Cohen-Charash & Spector, 2001; Colquitt et al., 2001). Of the moderators examined in our study, risk aver- sion yielded the most promising results, as it ampliWed the beneWcial eVects of both procedural and interper- sonal justice. Indeed, it was the only trait examined in our study that altered procedural eVects. Risk aversion was also the only trait that moderated both task perfor- mance and counterproductive behavior eVects in the pre- dicted manner. In contrast, risk aversion did not alter the eVects of distributive justice on either task performance or counterproductive behavior. Although uncertainty management theory deemphasizes the diVerences among the justice dimensions (Lind & Van den Bos, 2002; Van den Bos & Lind, 2002), it may be that distributive justice is less relevant to the management of uncertainty than procedural or interpersonal justice because it is more episodic, particularly when referenced to a one-time out- come or decision event. With regards to trust propensity, given that justice is used as a proxy for trust, we reasoned that justice would have less value to individuals who trusted “by default,” instead taking on more importance to the dispositionally suspicious. Indeed, our results showed that the eVects of interpersonal and distributive justice on task perfor- mance were more positive for individuals lower in trust propensity. Those eVects aside, two other aspects of our trust propensity results were contrary to predictions. First, trust propensity failed to moderate procedural jus- tice eVects on either task performance or counterproduc- tive behavior, which is somewhat surprising because many procedural justice rules (e.g., consistency, bias sup- pression, and ethicality) overlap conceptually with the integrity dimension of trustworthiness (Leventhal, 1980; Mayer et al., 1995). It may be that trust propensity would emerge as a signiWcant moderator of procedural justice eVects in Weld settings, where long-term relation- ships are prevalent. Second, the eVects of interpersonal justice on counterproductive behavior were actually stronger for individuals high in trust propensity, oppo- site to the task performance results. This result may be akin to Wndings by Brockner, Tyler, and Cooper-Schnei- der (1992) that individuals who were highly committed to an organization experienced greater negative reac- tions as a result of unfair treatment than those less com- mitted. That is, “the higher they are, the harder they fall” (Brockner et al., 1992). However, given that the results for task performance were in the opposite pattern, rather than non-signiWcant, this explanation may not be ade- quate. Future research is needed to provide insight into explaining these conXicting results. The third moderator examined in our study was trait morality. Using a trait-based form of the variable drawn from trait models of personality (de Raad et al., 1992; Hofstee et al., 1992), we found that the eVects of inter- personal and distributive justice on task performance were more positive for individuals high in trait morality. In contrast, trait morality did not moderate the eVects of procedural justice on task performance, contrary to our predictions. Folger (2001) argued that the moral accountability of justice tends to grow in ascending order from distributive to procedural to interactional. Thus, although distributive justice does have moral rele- vance (Folger, 1998, 2001), one would have expected the procedural interaction eVects to be stronger than the dis- tributive. It may be that our Wndings might have diVered had we manipulated procedural rules that were more morally charged than accuracy and consistency, such as bias suppression or ethicality (Leventhal, 1980). To gauge the signiWcant eVects for risk aversion, trust propensity, and trait morality, we explored two alterna- tive approaches to moderation of justice eVects. First, we examined two traits introduced by justice scholars: equity sensitivity and SBI. Both traits failed to moderate the eVects of justice, and their moderating eVects were much weaker than those of the three integrative theory traits. However, it should be noted that equity sensitivity was never intended to moderate the eVects of procedural or interpersonal justice. Similarly, the content of SBI, as measured using Schmitt and Maes’s (2000) scale, is decidedly distributive in nature, with the “befallen injus- tice” usually consisting of others receiving more of something of value. It therefore remains unclear how relevant SBI is to procedural and interpersonal justice. 124 J.A. Colquitt et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 100 (2006) 110–127 Second, we investigated the traits of the Big Five; how- ever, results were weaker compared to the results for the three integrative theory traits, with the justice £ Big Five product terms explaining less variance in the outcomes overall. Although Skarlicki et al.’s (1999) results found signiWcant interactions with Big Five variables, their results involved three-way interactions rather than the two-way eVects explored in our study. Still, it is notable that 6 years have passed since Skarlicki et al.’s (1999) study was published without further published work on justice £ Big Five interactions. It may be that such work has been conducted but yielded non-signiWcant results, creating a potential Wle drawer problem. Practical implications Our results oVer a number of practical implications. Task performance and counterproductive behavior clearly are important outcomes in any organization, as both impact bottom-line costs. Our results add to past research linking justice dimensions to those behaviors (Greenberg, 1990, 1993b, 2002; Konovsky & Cropanz- ano, 1991; Van den Bos et al., 1996). Inaccurate and inconsistent procedures, disrespectful interpersonal treatment, and unexpectedly low rewards impacted counterproductive behavior and task performance, though often in an interactive rather than main eVect fashion. Although justice principles can be trained (e.g., Skarl- icki & Latham, 1996), training initiatives often fail because of a lack of awareness of speciWc person and organizational variables that impact training eVective- ness. The “person analysis” phase of the training needs assessment is used to identify participant characteristics that make training more or less eVective, whereas the “organization analysis” explores contextual variables that can do the same. Our results could inform the per- son analysis, suggesting that justice training interven- tions would have particularly strong eVects when the leaders participating in the training oversee units with predominantly suspicious, cautious, and moral individu- als. However, organizations do not typically collect data on trust propensity, risk aversion, and trait morality, and it would be diYcult to characterize an entire unit on such personality traits. Our results might therefore inform the organization analysis, as justice trainers could consider contextual cues that trigger or amplify concerns about distrust, uncertainty, or moral issues. Limitations As in many laboratory studies, the framing of instruc- tions, the sequence of measurement, and the timing of measurements could impact the generalizability of results. For example, Harrison, McLaughlin, and Coalter (1996) showed that measures that reference fair- ness concepts are susceptible to scale ordering and con- text eVects. Our personality measures, some of which themselves referenced justice concepts, may be suscepti- ble to such biases. Context eVects could also have accounted for the small amount of manipulation spill- over that occurred among the justice manipulation checks. Although we removed this contamination by residualizing the aVected manipulations, a procedural remedy is usually preferred over a statistical one. In addition, our distributive justice manipulation varied fulWllment of expectations rather than outcome/input ratio comparisons. Although expectation fulWllment matches Blau’s (1964) conceptualization of distributive justice and has been used extensively in past research (Greenberg, 1993b; Van den Bos et al., 1998b), that type of manipulation may have constrained equity sensitiv- ity’s eVects, given that it is based on Adams’s (1965) theorizing. Other limitations center on the measures of some of our variables. Van den Bos et al. (1998a) showed that knowledge of trust moderated the eVects of justice, with justice being more impactful when trust was uncertain. Our measure of trust propensity is incapable of separat- ing trust uncertainty from trust valence, as suspicious individuals may either be uncertain about the trustwor- thiness of others or be certain that trustworthiness is lacking. In addition, our measure of counterproductive behavior could be interpreted in two ways: as intentional noncompliance with authority (one of the less serious forms of the construct) and outright theft (one of the more serious forms of the construct). Our results for counterproductive behavior may therefore fail to gener- alize to contexts where the retaliation is clearly serious in nature (e.g., theft of actual money). Finally, the most serious limitation of our study cen- ters on our trait morality measure. Recall that we chose to deWne morality as an intersection of high agreeable- ness and high conscientiousness (Hofstee et al., 1992). However, there are some interpretational ambiguities in trait models, mostly due to the presence of measure- ment error. For example, the adjectives “conscien- tious” and “agreeable” do not themselves fall squarely on the circumplex poles used to deWne those respective Big Five factors. Such ambiguities may hinder the con- struct validity of adjectives like “morality” that reside at the intersection of the conscientiousness and agree- ableness poles. Although future work can clarify many of these issues, there remains a limited amount of research on the Big Five circumplex. Moreover, it is important to note that Hofstee et al.’s (1992) model does not focus on morality per se, instead describing a large number of traits that represent blends of multiple Big Five factors. It is also important to note that the results for our cir- cumplex form of morality cannot be generalized to other forms of the construct, such as a Kohlbergian stage J.A. Colquitt et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 100 (2006) 110–127 125 approach. As stated previously, a trait approach diVers from a stage approach in that the former emphasizes diVerences across individuals while the latter emphasizes diVerences within individuals over time (Walker, 2002). However, it may be that stage models such as Kohl- berg’s would also be useful for examining moderating eVects of justice (for an example, see Greenberg, 2002). Future researchers utilizing such an approach would beneWt from using appropriate stage measures such as the DeWning Issues Test 2 (Rest, Narvaez, Thoma, & Bebeau, 1999). Suggestions for future research Perhaps the most fruitful area for future research con- cerns one additional limitation of our study. Our concep- tual model in Fig. 1 includes three diVerent mechanisms through which personality traits could moderate justice eVects: sensitivity to justice concerns, deliberate rumina- tion on justice information, and likelihood of behavioral response. Our study did not assess those mechanisms, however. It therefore remains an empirical question whether those mechanisms do explain moderation eVects at all, or whether only one or two of the processes is neces- sary for interactions to emerge. Although our study was fairly comprehensive in its coverage of multiple justice dimensions and its inclusion of several personality traits, some gaps in our coverage highlight other areas for future research. For example, the “belief in a just world” may be relevant to the should counterfactual and to the mechanisms in Fig. 1. It may be that individuals with strong just world beliefs attend more to justice because they, like moral individuals, are more concerned with fairness in general. However, it may also be that individuals with strong just world beliefs attend less to issues of fairness because they believe that things will “work out” in the end. Future research should also explore personality mod- erators in conjunction with the other sub-facet of interac- tional justice: informational justice. We did not include informational justice in the present study for both practi- cal and conceptual reasons. Practically speaking, includ- ing informational justice would have doubled the number of experimental conditions in an already complex study. Conceptually, we felt that some of our personality traits were more relevant to interpersonal justice, given that it is morally charged and holds special relevance to the integ- rity and benevolence forms of trustworthiness (Folger, 2001; Mayer et al., 1995). However, informational justice is germane to the could and should portions of fairness theory (Folger & Cropanzano, 2001; Shaw, Wild, & Colquitt, 2003) and its eVects could be moderated by traits that capture the likelihood of asking “why?” ques- tions (e.g., curiosity, need for cognition). Future research should also explore personality mod- erators of the two-way justice interactions often observed in the justice literature. Skarlicki et al.’s (1999) results showed that neuroticism and agreeableness mod- erated the interaction between distributive and interac- tional justice, while Hagedoorn et al.’s (2002) showed that just world beliefs moderated the interaction between distributive and procedural justice. Such work allows justice scholars to assess the generalizability of such interactions across personality types. It may be that more complex interactions could help explain some of the unexpected patterns in our two-way results. For example, some of the interactions were symmetric in nature, with fair treatment resulting in lower perfor- mance or more counterproductive behavior at certain personality patterns. Although such patterns are surpris- ing in the context of two-way interactions, they may make more sense in conjunction with higher-order inter- action patterns. Finally, it is important to point out that the interac- tions observed in our study could be interpreted in a diVerent way—that justice dimensions moderate the relationships between personality traits and counter- productive behavior and task performance. The signiW- cant product terms can be interpreted in either fashion, as can the plots represented in the Wgures. It may be that organizational justice can be used to clarify incon- sistent behavioral eVects within the trust propensity, risk aversion, or morality literatures. For example, unfair treatment may be relevant to the principle of trait activation (e.g., Tett & Gutterman, 2000), with fairness violations creating situational cues that enhance the likelihood of trait expression. To our knowledge, the justice dimensions have rarely been cast as moderators in past research, leaving open a poten- tially fruitful area for future theorizing and empirical study. References Adams, J. S. (1965). Inequity in social exchange. In L. Berkowitz (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 2, pp. 267–299). New York: Academic Press. Bies, R. J., & Moag, J. F. (1986). Interactional justice: Communication criteria of fairness. In R. J. Lewicki, B. H. Sheppard, & M. H. Bazer- man (Eds.), Research on negotiations in organizations (Vol. 1, pp. 43–55). Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. Bies, R. J., & Tripp, T. M. (1995). Beyond distrust: “Getting even” and the need for revenge. In R. M. Kramer & T. R. Tyler (Eds.), Trust in organizations: Frontiers of theory and research (pp. 246–260). Thou- sand Oaks, CA: Sage. Blau, P. (1964). Exchange and power in social life. New York: Wiley. Brockner, J., Heuer, L., Siegel, P. A., Wiesenfeld, B., Martin, C., Grover, S., et al. (1998). The moderating eVect of self-esteem in reaction to voice: Converging evidence from Wve studies. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 75, 394–407. Brockner, J., Tyler, T. R., & Cooper-Schneider, R. (1992). The inXuence of prior commitment to an institution on reactions to perceived unfairness: The higher they are, the harder they fall. Administrative Science Quarterly, 37, 241–261. 126 J.A. Colquitt et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 100 (2006) 110–127 Cable, D. M., & Judge, T. A. (1994). Pay preferences and job search decisions: A person-organization Wt perspective. Personnel Psychol- ogy, 47, 317–348. Cohen, J., Cohen, P., West, S. G., & Aiken, L. S. (2003). Applied multiple regression/correlation analysis for the behavioral sciences. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Cohen-Charash, Y., & Spector, P. E. (2001). The role of justice in orga- nizations: A meta-analysis. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 86, 278–321. Colquitt, J. A. (2001). On the dimensionality of organizational justice: A construct validation of a measure. Journal of Applied Psychology, 86, 386–400. Colquitt, J. A., Conlon, D. E., Wesson, M. J., Porter, C., & Ng, K. Y. (2001). Justice at the millennium: A meta-analytic review of 25 years of organizational justice research. Journal of Applied Psychol- ogy, 86, 425–445. Colquitt, J. A., Greenberg, J., & Zapata-Phelan, C. P. (2005). What is organizational justice?: A historical overview. In J. Greenberg & J. A. Colquitt (Eds.), The handbook of organizational justice (pp. 3– 56). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Costa, P. T., Jr., & McCrae, R. R. (1992). Revised NEO Personality Inventory (NEO-PI-R) and NEO Five-Factor Inventory (NEO- FFI) professional manual. Odessa, FL: Psychological Assessment Resources. Cropanzano, R., Byrne, Z. S., Bobocel, D. R., & Rupp, D. E. (2001). Moral virtues, fairness heuristics, social entities, and other denizens of organizational justice. Journal of Vocational Behavior, 58, 164–209. de Raad, B., Hendriks, A. J., & Hofstee, W. K. (1992). Towards a reWned structure of personality traits. European Journal of Person- ality, 6, 301–319. Eisenberger, R., Cotterell, N., & Marvel, J. (1987). Reciprocation ideol- ogy. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 53, 743–750. Folger, R. (1998). Fairness as a moral virtue. In M. Schminke (Ed.), Managerial ethics: Morally managing people and processes (pp. 13– 34). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Folger, R. (2001). Fairness as deonance. In S. W. Gilliland, D. D. Steiner, & D. P. Skarlicki (Eds.), Theoretical and cultural perspec- tives on organizational justice (pp. 3–34). Greenwich, CT: Informa- tion Age Publishing. Folger, R., & Cropanzano, R. (2001). Fairness theory: Justice as accountability. In J. Greenberg & R. Cropanzano (Eds.), Advances in organizational justice (pp. 89–118). Stanford, CA: Stanford Uni- versity Press. Folger, R., Cropanzano, R., & Goldman, B. (2005). What is the rela- tionship between justice and morality. In J. Greenberg & J. A. Col- quitt (Eds.), Handbook of organizational justice (pp. 215–245). Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. Goldberg, L. R. (1990). An alternative “description of personality”: The Big-Five factor structure. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 59, 1216–1229. Greenberg, J. (1990). Employee theft as a reaction to underpayment nequity: The hidden cost of pay cuts. Journal of Applied Psychol- ogy, 75, 561–568. Greenberg, J. (1993a). The social side of fairness: Interpersonal and informational classes of organizational justice. In R. Cropanzano (Ed.), Justice in the workplace: Approaching fairness in human resource management (pp. 79–103). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Greenberg, J. (1993b). Stealing in the name of justice: Informational and interpersonal moderators of theft reactions to underpayment inequity. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 54, 81–103. Greenberg, J. (2002). Who stole the money, and when? Individual and situational determinants of employee theft. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 89, 985–1003. Hagedoorn, M., Buunk, B. P., & van de Vliert, E. (2002). Do just world believers process unfair authoritative decisions diVerently? Applied Psychology: An International Review, 51, 126–145. Harrison, D. A., McLaughlin, M. E., & Coalter, T. M. (1996). Context, cognition, and common method variance: Psychometric and verbal protocol evidence. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 68, 246–261. Heuer, L., Blumenthal, E., Douglas, A., & Weinblatt, T. (1999). A deserv- ingness approach to respect as a relationally based fairness judgment. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 25, 1279–1292. Hofstee, W. K., de Raad, B., & Goldberg, L. R. (1992). Integration of the Big Five and circumplex approaches to trait structure. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 63, 146–163. Hogan, J., & Roberts, B. W. (1996). Issues and non-issues in the Wdelity-bandwidth debate. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 17, 627–637. Homans, G. C. (1961). Social behaviour: Its elementary forms. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Huseman, R. C., HatWeld, J. D., & Miles, E. W. (1987). A new perspec- tive on equity theory: The Equity Sensitivity construct. Academy of Management Review, 12, 222–234. International Personality Item Pool (2001). A scientiWc collabora- tory for the development of advanced measures of personality traits and other individual diVerences (http://ipip.ori.org/). Internet Web Site. John, O. P., Donahue, E. M., & Kentle, R. L. (1991). The Big FiveInven- tory—Versions 4a and 54. Berkeley, CA: University of California, Berkeley, Institute of Personality and Social Research. Joy, V. L., & Witt, L. A. (1992). Delay of gratiWcation as a moderator of the procedural justice-distributive justice relationship. Group and Organization Management, 17, 297–308. Judge, T. A., & Larsen, R. J. (2001). Dispositional aVect and job satis- faction: A review and theoretical extension. Organizational Behav- ior and Human Decision Processes, 86, 67–98. Kanfer, R. (1991). Motivation theory and industrial and organiza- tional psychology. In M. D. Dunnette & L. M. Hough (Eds.), Hand- book of industrial and organizational psychology (Vol. 1, pp. 75– 170). Palo Alto, CA: Consulting Psychologists Press. King, W. C., & Miles, E. W. (1994). The measurement of equity sensi- tivity. Journal of Occupational and Organizational Psychology, 67, 133–142. King, W. C., Miles, E. W., & Day, D. D. (1993). A test and reWnement of the equity sensitivity construct. Journal of Organizational Behav- ior, 14, 301–317. Kohlberg, L. (1984). The psychology of moral development. San Fran- cisco, CA: Harper and Row. Konovsky, M. A., & Cropanzano, R. (1991). Perceived fairness of employee drug testing as a predictor of employee attitudes and job performance. Journal of Applied Psychology, 76, 698–707. Leventhal, G. S. (1980). What should be done with equity theory? New approaches to the study of fairness in social relationships. In K. Ger- gen, M. Greenberg, & R. Willis (Eds.), Social exchange: Advances in theory and research (pp. 27–55). New York: Plenum Press. Lind, E. A. (2001). Fairness heuristic theory: Justice judgments as piv- otal cognitions in organizational relations. In J. Greenberg & R. Cropanzano (Eds.), Advances in organizational justice (pp. 56–88). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Lind, E. A., & Van den Bos, K. (2002). When fairness works: Toward a general theory of uncertainty management. In B. M. Staw & R. M. Kramer (Eds.), Research in organizational behavior (Vol. 24, pp. 181–223). Boston, MA: Elsevier. Maehr, M. L., & Videbeck, R. (1968). Predisposition to risk and persis- tence under varying reinforcement-success schedules. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 9, 96–100. Major, B., & Deaux, K. (1982). Individual diVerences in justice behav- ior. In J. Greenberg & R. L. Cohen (Eds.), Equity and justice in social behavior (pp. 43–76). New York: Academic Press. Mayer, R. C., Davis, J. H., & Schoorman, F. D. (1995). An integrative model of organizational trust. Academy of Management Review, 20, 709–734. http://ipip.ori.org/ http://ipip.ori.org/ J.A. Colquitt et al. / Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes 100 (2006) 110–127 127 Ones, D. S. (1994). The construct validity of integrity tests. Unpublished doctoral dissertation, University of Iowa. Perdue, B. C., & Summers, J. O. (1986). Checking the success of manip- ulations in marketing experiments. Journal of Marketing Research, 23, 317–326. Pizarro, D. A., Uhlmann, E., & Bloom, P. (2003). Causal deviance and the attribution of moral responsibility. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 39, 653–660. Rest, J., Narvaez, D., Thoma, S. J., & Bebeau, M. J. (1999). DIT-2: Devising and testing a new instrument of moral judgment. Journal of Educational Psychology, 91, 644–659. Saucier, G., & Goldberg, L. R. (1996). Evidence for the Big Five in analyses of familiar English personality adjectives. European Jour- nal of Personality, 10, 61–77. Schmitt, M. J., & Dorfel, M. (1999). Procedural injustice at work, jus- tice sensitivity, job satisfaction and psychosomatic well-being. European Journal of Social Psychology, 29, 443–453. Schmitt, M. J., & Maes, J. (2000). Scales for measuring justice sensitivity from three perspectives. Unpublished manuscript, University of Trier, Germany. Schmitt, M. J., Neumann, R., & Montada, L. (1995). Dispositional sen- sitivity to befallen injustice. Social Justice Research, 8, 385–407. Schmitt, N., & Stults, D. M. (1985). Factors deWned by negatively keyed items: The result of careless respondents? Applied Psychological Measurement, 9, 367–373. Schneider, B. (1983). Interactional psychology and organizational behavior. In L. L. Cummings & B. M. Staw (Eds.), Research in orga- nizational behavior (Vol.5, pp. 1–31). Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. Shaw, J. C., Wild, R. E., & Colquitt, J. A. (2003). To justify or excuse?: A meta-analysis of the eVects of explanations. Journal of Applied Psychology, 88, 444–458. Skarlicki, D. P., Folger, R., & Tesluk, P. (1999). Personality as a moder- ator in the relationship between fairness and retaliation. Academy of Management Journal, 42, 100–108. Skarlicki, D. P., & Latham, G. P. (1996). Increasing citizenship behav- ior within a labor union: A test of organizational justice theory. Journal of Applied Psychology, 81, 161–169. Sweeney, P. D., & McFarlin, D. B. (1993). Workers’ evaluations of the “ends” and “means”: An examination of four models of distribu- tive and procedural justice. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 55, 23–40. Sweeney, P. D., McFarlin, D. B., & Cotton, J. L. (1991). Locus of con- trol as a moderator of the relationship between perceived inXuence and procedural justice. Human Relations, 44, 333–342. Tett, R. P., & Gutterman, H. A. (2000). Situation trait relevance, trait expression, and cross-situational consistency: Testing a principle of trait activation. Journal of Research in Personality, 34, 397–423. Thibaut, J., & Walker, L. (1975). Procedural justice: A psychological analysis. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Turillo, C. J., Folger, R., Lavelle, J. J., Umphress, E. E., & Gee, J. O. (2002). Is virtue its own reward? Self-sacriWcial decisions for the sake of fairness. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Pro- cesses, 89, 839–865. Tyler, T. R., & Lind, E. A. (1992). A relational model of authority in groups. In M. P. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psy- chology (Vol. 25, pp. 115–191). San Diego, CA: Academic Press. Van den Bos, K. (2001a). Fairness heuristic theory: Assessing the infor- mation to which people are reacting has a pivotal role in under- standing organizational justice. In S. Gilliland, D. Steiner, & D. Skarlicki (Eds.), Theoretical and cultural perspectives on organiza- tional justice (pp. 63–84). Greenwich, CT: Information Age Publish- ing. Van den Bos, K. (2001b). Uncertainty management: The inXuence of uncertainty salience on reactions to perceived procedural fairness. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 80, 931–941. Van den Bos, K., Bruins, J., Wilke, H. A. M., & Dronkert, E. (1999). Sometimes unfair procedures have nice aspects: On the psychology of the fair process eVect. Journal of Personality and Social Psychol- ogy, 77, 324–336. Van den Bos, K., & Lind, E. A. (2002). Uncertainty management by means of fairness judgments. In M. P. Zanna (Ed.), Advances in experimental social psychology (Vol. 34, pp. 1–60). Boston, MA: Elsevier. Van den Bos, K., Maas, M., Waldring, I. E., & Semin, G. R. (2003). Toward understanding the psychology of reactions to perceived fairness: The role of aVect intensity. Social Justice Research, 16, 151–168. Van den Bos, K., Vermunt, R., & Wilke, H. A. M. (1996). The consis- tency rule and the voice eVect: The inXuence of expectations on procedural fairness judgments and performance. European Journal of Social Psychology, 26, 411–428. Van den Bos, K., Wilke, H. A. M., & Lind, E. A. (1998a). When do we need procedural fairness? The role of trust in authority. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 75, 1449–1458. Van den Bos, K., Wilke, H. A. M., Lind, E. A., & Vermunt, R. (1998b). Evaluating outcomes by means of the fair process eVect: Evidence for diVerent processes in fairness and satisfaction judgments. Jour- nal of Personality and Social Psychology, 74, 1493–1503. Walker, L. J. (2002). The model and the measure: An appraisal of the Minnesota approach to moral development. Journal of Moral Edu- cation, 31, 353–367. Witt, L. A., Kacmar, K. M., & Andrews, M. C. (2001). The interac- tive eVects of procedural justice and exchange ideology on supervisor-rated commitment. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 22, 505–515. Zuckerman, M., & Reis, H. T. (1978). Comparison of three models for predicting altruistic behavior. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 36, 498–510. Justice and personality: Using integrative theories to derive moderators of justice effects Past research on moderation of justice effects Distributive justice research Procedural justice research Interactional justice research Applying integrative justice theories to personality moderators of justice effects A brief review of integrative justice theories Fairness heuristic theory Uncertainty management theory Fairness theory Which traits worthy of study can be derived from the integrative theories? Trust propensity Risk aversion Morality Alternative approaches to moderation of justice effects Method Sample Procedure Integrative theory traits Trust propensity Risk aversion Trait morality Confirmatory factor analysis Alternative moderators Equity sensitivity Sensitivity to Befallen injustice Big Five dimensions Outcome measures Task performance Counterproductive behavior Manipulation checks Results Manipulation checks Results for integrative theory traits Results for alternative approaches to moderation of justice effects Discussion Practical implications Limitations Suggestions for future research References work_k5cc45hvovgfjllvpdgzghoh7y ---- 西南交通大学学报 第 55 卷 第 4 期 2020 年 8 月 JOURNAL OF SOUTHWEST JIAOTONG UNIVERSITY Vol. 55 No. 4 Aug. 2020 ISSN: 0258-2724 DOI:10.35741/issn.0258-2724.55.4.8 Research article Social Sciences LEADER–MEMBER EXCHANGE IN MEDIATING INTERPERSONAL JUSTICE AND INFORMATIONAL JUSTICE CLIMATE TOWARD COUNTERPRODUCTIVE WORK BEHAVIOR 调解人际正义和信息正义的领导者-成员之间的交流,以实现反 生产性工作 Yuni Siswanti a, * , Heru Kurnianto Tjahjono b , Arif Hartono c , Wisnu Prajogo d a Department of Management, Faculty of Economics and Business, Universitas Pembangunan Nasional “Veteran” Yogyakarta Yogyakarta, Indonesia, yuni.siswanti@upnyk.ac.id b Department of Management, Faculty of Economics and Business, Universitas Muhammadiyah Yogyakarta Yogyakarta, Indonesia c Department of Management, Faculty of Business and Economics, Universitas Islam Indonesia Yogyakarta, Indonesia d Department of Management, STIE YKPN Yogyakarta Yogyakarta, Indonesia Received: April 25, 2020 ▪ Review: June 21, 2020 ▪ Accepted: July 6, 2020 This article is an open access article distributed under the terms and conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0) Abstract This cross-level study (individual level) examines the influence of interpersonal justice climate and informational justice climate (unit level) on counterproductive work behavior (individual level). The study also examines the role of leader–member exchange (individual level) in mediating the influence of these climates on counterproductive work behavior. The study was carried out by distributing a questionnaire to non-civil-servant lecturers in three new state universities in Indonesia. Of the questionnaires distributed, 399 were returned completely filled out and were then processed using hierarchical linear modeling. Hierarchical linear modeling is the appropriate analysis tool for examining cross-level models in which there is variance at both the individual level and the group level, with individual-level outcomes. The hierarchical linear modeling method still considers variance both within and between units and the role of both individuals and units simultaneously. The instruments were tested using confirmatory factor analysis, and reliability tests were carried out by looking at the coefficient of Cronbach’s alpha. The results of the hypothesis test show that while interpersonal and informational justice climates do not have an influence on counterproductive work behavior (H1 and H2 not accepted), they do have a significant influence on leader–member exchange (H3 and H4 accepted), which itself has a positive influence on counterproductive work behavior (H5 accepted). The test results for H6 and H7 show leader–member exchange fully mediates the influence of interpersonal and informational justice climate on counterproductive work behavior. The results of this study encourage further discussion and mailto:yuni.siswanti@upnyk.ac.id http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0 Siswanti et al. / Journal of Southwest Jiaotong University / Vol.55 No.4 Aug. 2020 2 open opportunities for cross-level research with different variables and objects. Keywords: Interpersonal Justice Climate, Informational Justice Climate, Counterproductive Work Behavior, Leader-Member Exchange, Cross-Level Research 摘要 这项跨层次的研究(个人)考察了人际公正气氛和信息公正气氛(单位层次)对适得其反的 工作行为(个人层次)的影响。该研究还研究了领导者-成员交流(个人)在调解这些气候对适得 其反的工作行为的影响中的作用。这项研究是通过向印度尼西亚三所新州立大学的非公务员讲师 分发问卷调查表进行的。在分发的问卷中,有 399 份完全填满,然后使用分层线性建模进行处理 。分层线性建模是检查跨级别模型的适当分析工具,在跨级别模型中,个人级别和组级别都有差 异,而个人级别的结果也是如此。分层线性建模方法仍然考虑单位内部和单位之间的差异以及个 人和单位的角色。仪器通过验证性因子分析进行了测试,可靠性测试通过查看克伦巴赫α系数进 行。假设检验的结果表明,尽管人际关系和信息正义的气氛对适得其反的工作行为没有影响(H1 和 H2 不被接受),但它们确实对领导成员之间的交流有重大影响(H3 和 H4 被接受),本身会对 适得其反的工作行为产生积极影响(接受 H5)。H6 和 H7 的测试结果表明,领导成员之间的交流 充分调解了人际和信息正义氛围对适得其反的工作行为的影响。这项研究的结果鼓励进行进一步 的讨论,并为具有不同变量和对象的跨层次研究提供机会。 关键词: 人际公正气氛,信息公正气氛,适得其反的工作行为,领导成员交流,跨层次研究 I. INTRODUCTION Counterproductive work behavior (CWB) has become an increasingly important subject of study because it can be incredibly costly to overcome. Previous researchers have used various terms to describe CWB, such as deviant work behavior [1], [2], aggressive behavior [3], [4], [5], antisocial behavior [6], and counterproductive work behavior [7], [8]. All these terms have the same meaning—negative work behavior by an employee that can harm or endanger the organization and its members. The study conducted by [5], [9], [10] concluded CWB has a negative impact on both the employee and the organization. Therefore, studying the factors that cause CWB is critical to reduce the costs borne by the organization [1], [11]. One of the factors triggering the emergence of CWB is the contextual factor, which involves several surrounding variables that have the potential to be involved in the process of dishonesty in decision-making [12]. These factors include labor force, economic disparity, opportunities to thrive, and organizational justice. [13], [14], [15] stated that the individual approach fails to include social context when involved in the formation of perceptions of justice. In a unit or group, each member interacts with each other, observes behavior with one another, and is bound in understanding to build shared perceptions to evaluate fairness applied within the organization [16], [17], [18]. Consistent with this statement, today’s research suggests to view justice as a distinct property, which can be formed on the basis of interaction between each member in the same unit/group. This formed perception is called justice climate. [16] are the researchers who first introduced the term. According to [16], justice climate is group/unit level cognition about how a working group as a whole is treated. An understanding of justice climate and its impact on employee behavior was further investigated by [19], [20], [21]. II. LITERATURE REVIEW A. The Relationship between Interpersonal Justice Climate and Counterproductive Work Behavior 1) Basic Theory of Interpersonal Justice Climate Researchers of organizational behavior, particularly regarding organizational justice, have identified four types of organizational justice: distributive justice, procedural justice, interpersonal justice, and informational justice [22]. Interactional justice according to [23], [24] is divided into two forms of justice, interpersonal justice and informational justice. 3 Interpersonal justice is a perception of justice felt by a group of workers regarding interpersonal treatment that is given during the implementation of procedures that existed before and results. Interpersonal justice considers the perception of a group of personnel regarding the justice on the issue of how they are treated. Impolite and unfair treatment by leaders causes a group of members (work teams) to experience a decrease in motivation and job satisfaction, as well as other negative behaviors [77]. 2) Counterproductive Work Behavior (CWB) Theory According to [25], CWB is work behavior that interferes with the organization or members of the organization. [26] grouped CWB into eleven categories: (1) theft and behavior related to it; (2) damage to organization’s belongings; (3) misuse of information; (4) abuse of time and resources; (5) dangerous behavior; (6) low attendance; (7) low quality of work; (8) use of alcohol; (9) drug use; (10) committing inappropriate verbal actions; and (11) carrying out inappropriate physical actions. Interpersonal and informational justice have a significant negative influence on CWB that aimed at organizations and interpersonal/other individuals [27], [28]. This means that interpersonal and informational justice will reduce the CWB. The results from previous studies [15], [20], [29], [30] showed that interactional justice climate (interpersonal and informational justice) that is formed in social exchange relationships will have a significant effect on employee attitudes and behavior (job satisfaction, organizational commitment, work stress, OCB, deviant behavior, and CWB). B. The Relationship between Informational Justice Climate and Counterproductive Work Behavior 1) Basic Theory of Informational Justice Climate According to [23], [24], an informational justice climate is when a group’s perception of information is used as a basis for decision making. Informational justice motivates the feelings of respect by others through clear information-giving mechanisms within the organization. [17] stated that both procedural justice and interactional justice (interpersonal and informational) can predict employee attitudes and the desires of employees, including counterproductive work behavior (CWB). Previous research [24], [31] stated that interactional justice is the most powerful predictor of predicting CWB compared to the other two dimensions of organizational justice. The statement of the previous studies was strengthened by [27], [28] that low perception of interactional justice may cause CWV aimed at both the organizations and at other individuals. C. Interpersonal Justice Climate-Leader- Member Exchange (LMX)-CWB 1) Basic Theory of Leader-Member Exchange The basic principle of LMX theory is that leaders form a unique relationship with the members [32], [33], [85]. High-quality LMX relationships between the leader and member are characterized by emotional exchanges based on mutual trust and respect, while low-quality LMX relationships have economic exchange characteristics [32], [33], [34]. According to [35], [36], LMX has two dimensions. The first dimension is the approach to build good relations with employees, which consists of loyalty, support, and trust. The second dimension that becomes the basis of LMX is coupling, which focuses on the attitudes of leaders towards members that include addressing, influence, allocation, freedom of expression, and innovation. These dimensions form the LMX theory, as one of the leadership theory to measure the relationship between leaders and members in an organization [37]. [38] found a positive and significant relationship of the dimensions of organizational justice (procedural, distributive, interpersonal, and informational justice) with LMX. In addition, [39] stated that procedural, distributive, and interactional justice has a strong and significant relationship with the quality of LMX. The results from the study of [40] showed that interpersonal justice has a significant influence on LMX. The high quality of LMX reduces the CWB [41], [42], [43]. D. Informational Justice Climate -Leader- Member Exchange (LMX)-CWB The study from [28] found that LMX fully mediates the relationship between interpersonal and informational justice with counterproductive work behavior (both towards supervisors and towards the organization). E. Hypothesis H1: Interpersonal Justice Climate has a negative influence on Counterproductive Work Behavior H2: Informational Justice Climate has a negative influence on Counterproductive Work Behavior H3: Interpersonal Justice Climate has a Siswanti et al. / Journal of Southwest Jiaotong University / Vol.55 No.4 Aug. 2020 4 positive influence on LMX H4: Informational Justice Climate has a positive influence on LMX H5: LMX has a negative influence on Counterproductive Work Behavior H6: Leader Member Exchange (LMX) mediates the influence of Interpersonal Justice Climate towards Counterproductive Work Behavior H7: Leader Member Exchange (LMX) mediates the influence of Informational Justice Climate towards Counterproductive Work Behavior. Figure 1. Research model III. RESEARCH METHOD A. Population and Sample The population of this study is non-civil servant lecturer from 3 new state universities (PTNB) in Indonesia. The number of population and sample of this study can be seen on Table 1. The sampling technique is done using Slovin formula. From the total of 563 people, the minimum sample is 233 people. Table 1. Population and sample of study No. University Population Number of study program (group) Sample 1. PTNB 1 187 16 143 2. PTNB 2 167 16 100 3. PTNB 3 209 23 156 Total 563 73 399 B. Measurement To measure interpersonal and informational justice climate, this study uses the instrument developed by [44] which consists of 4 items for each variable. CWB is measured in individual level with the instrument developed by [26], which consists of 27 items. All instruments are measured using 6 point scale Adjusted Likert Scale (scale 1 = strongly disagree; scale 6 = strongly agree). C. Instrument Test The instruments are examined with validity test using Confirmatory Factor Analysis and reliability test using Cronbach’s Alpha. The limit of reliability test according to [45] is α 0.7; and if α = 0.6, it can be accepted in exploratory research. D. Hypothesis Test Method The hypothesis test is carried out using Hierarchical Linear Modeling (HLM) because this study examine variables with different level of analysis (cross-level), namely unit level (interpersonal and informational justice climate) and individual level (CWB) (2-1-1). This model is developed by [46]. HLM is the appropriate analysis tool to examine cross-level model, in which there is variance at the individual level and group level with individual level outcomes. The HLM method still considers variance within units and variance between units. This method still considers the role of both individuals and units at the same time. IV. RESULT A. Respondents’ Characteristics The results of the descriptive test in Table 2 shows that most respondents are on the productive age by 46-50 years old (27.3%); female (56.6%); have master degree (80.5%); and have been working for 21-25 years (30.1%). Table 2. Respondents’ characteristics Profile Category Number Percentage Age 26 – 30 years old 12 3.0 31 – 35 years old 76 19.0 36 – 40 years old 62 15.5 41 – 45 years old 84 21.1 46 – 50 years old 109 27.3 51 – 55 years old 35 8.8 56 – 60 years old 18 4.5 5  60 years old 3 .8 Gender Male 173 43.4 Female 226 56.6 Education Master Degree 321 80.5 Doctoral Degree 78 19.5 Working time 1-5 years 31 7.8 6-10 years 71 17.8 11-15 years 70 17.5 16-20 years 72 18.0 21-25 years 120 30.1 26-30 years 28 7.0 > 30 years 7 1.8 Total 399 100.0 B. Validity and Reliability Test Results For Interpersonal Justice Climate (4 items), 2 items are valid because their value is above 0.6 (loading factor > = 0.6). For Distributive Justice Climate (5 items), all items are valid. The test results for confirmatory factor analysis (CFA) for CWB demonstrate that from 21 total items, 15 items are valid and 6 items are invalid. Thus, these 6 items are not included in the subsequent data processing [47]. The reliability test results indicated that three research variables are reliable, having a Cronbach’s Alpha coefficient of > 0.6. Table 3. Descriptive statistic and correlation No. Individual level variable Average Perception of average score Standard deviation 1 2 3 1. Leader-member exchange (LMX) 4.3743 High .84452 -0,310** 2. Counterproductive work behavior (CWB) 1.5646 Lowest .46672 Unit level variable 1. Interpersonal justice climate 4.9586 High .85738 - 2. Informational justice climate 4.5213 High .92368 Note: **p < 0,01; *p < 0,05 C. Unit Level Data Testing The two unit level variables in this study are the procedural justice climate and the distributive justice climate. The data collected is based on individual perception, so a justification for aggregation is needed to make these unit-level variables. When the aggregation is conducted and results do not meet the minimum score, the group or work unit is deemed not suitable to be used as a study sample. The stages of aggregation of individual data into group data are as follows: a) The first step of data aggregation refers to the value of the Inter-Rater Agreement (IRA). The Inter-Rater Agreement is an index of approval degrees in a separate work unit. IRA calculation is applied to each work group for each variable. IRA testing has a minimum score (cutoff) that must be met. All work units must have a minimum score > 0.70. 55 work groups or units have predetermined score standards (cutoff > 0.70), so they meet the requirements to be included in the analysis testing process. b) Inter-Class Correlation (ICC) (1) is calculated for each justice climate (procedural and distributive). The score generated from the ICC test (1) must be ≥ 0.05; that is, the variance between groups is greater than the variants within the group. The ICC value (1) represents sufficient variance between groups. c) ICC score (2) must be > 0.60, which is the ICC standard score (2) [48]. If standard scores are met the working group or unit, there are average eligibility score given by each working group member to represent score at the group level. The estimation result shows that ICC score (2) meets the standard value of 0.60 for each justice climate. Table 4. Unit level data testing result Siswanti et al. / Journal of Southwest Jiaotong University / Vol.55 No.4 Aug. 2020 6 No. Variable rwg a (average) rwg (median) ICC b (1) ICC (2) 1. Interactional justice climate 0,8160 0,8092 0,582 0,736 2. Informational justice climate 0,8142 0,8000 0,802 0,961 a Interrater agreement b Intraclass correlation coefficient d) Before testing the hypothesis with HLM, the unconstrained (null) dependent variable model must be tested to determine the variance of the dependent variable between study groups (between-group variance) as a condition that must be met before cross-level testing. The null model testing is conducted on variables that are being the consequences of interpersonal justice climate, informational justice climate, namely CWB. Table 5 shows the unconstrained model result of the two output variables. The test result shows a significant chi-square value for CWB ( ؘ χ2 = 73.51841; p < 0.05). These results indicate that there are differences in outcome variables between work units, so that cross-level hypothesis testing using HLM analysis tools can be conducted. Table 5. Summary of unconstrained testing results (null model) Variable Chi-square (χ2) σ2 dan τ ICC = τ/(τ + σ2) Description Leader-member exchange (LMX) 101.82383 0,63851 and 0,00825 0.012756 The result of the unconstrained model shows a significant chi-square and ICC, i.e. there are differences in variance between work units/ study programs on each dependent variable, so that HLM analysis can be proceed. Counterproductive work behavior (CWB) 73.51841 0,20973 and 0,01142 0.051639 D. Hypothesis Test Hypothesis test consists of: (1) testing the cross-level influence of interpersonal justice climate towards CWB, and (2) informational justice climate towards CWB. The test for the direct influence of unit level variable towards individual variable in HLM is known as intercepts-as-outcomes model. The results of the test of H1, H2, H3, H4, and H5 can be seen in Table 6. Table 6. Summary of the direct test results of unit level variables with individual level output variable Variable CWB H LMX H Γ S.E P-value γ S.E P-value Unit level Interpersonal justice climate -0.042 0.069 0.546 H1 0.557*** 0.136 <0.001 H3 Informational justice climate -0.052 0.053 0.331 H2 0.544*** 0.087 <0.001 H4 Individual level LMX -0.174*** 0.051 <0.001 H5 Note: ***p < 0,001; **p < 0.05 The test result of the cross-level influence of interpersonal justice climate towards CWB shows no significant influence (γ = -0.042; SE = 0.069; p < 0.546) (H1 is not supported). The test result of the cross-level influence of informational justice climate towards CWB shows no significant influence (γ = -0.052; SE = 0.053; p < 0.331) (H1 is not supported). The test result of the cross-level influence of interpersonal justice climate towards LMX shows significant positive influence (γ = 0.557; SE = 0.136; p < 0.001) (H3 is supported). The test result of the cross-level influence of informational justice climate towards LMX shows significant positive influence (γ = 0.544; SE = 0.087; p < 0.001) (H4 is supported). The test of the influence of LMX on CWB shows negative significant influence (γ = -0.174; SE = 0.051; p < 0.001) (H5 is supported). The steps for H6 testing can be seen in Table 7. 7 Table 7. Steps for Hypothesis 6 testing Step Direct influence (γ) Influence after mediation (γ) Note Step 1: The influence of IKIT on CWB γ = -0.042 p < 0.546 Not significant Step 2: The influence of IKIT on LMX γ = 0.557** p < 0.001 Significant Step 3: The influence of LMX on CWB γ = -0.174 p < 0.001 Significant Step 4: The influence of IKIT and LMX on CWB γ = - 0.186 p < 0.001 Significant The first step is testing the influence of interpersonal justice climate on CWB. This step is H1 testing and the result is not significant (γ = -0.042; SE = 0.069; p < 0.546). The second step is testing the influence of interpersonal justice climate on LMX (H3), and the result is significantly positive (γ = 0.557; SE = 0.136; p < 0,001). The third step is testing the influence of LMX on CWB (H5) and the result is significantly negative (γ = -0.174; SE = 0.051; p < 0.001). The fourth step is testing interpersonal justice climate on CWB and including LMX as mediating variable, and the result is significantly negative ( γ = - 0.186; p < 0.001). Therefore, H6 is supported, which means that LMX fully mediates the influence of interpersonal justice climate on CWB (MacKinnon, 2008). As for the steps for H7 testing can be seen in Table 8. Table 8. Steps for Hypothesis 7 testing Steps Direct influence (γ) Influence after mediation (γ) Note Step 1: The influence of IKIF on CWB γ = 0.163 p < 0.331 Not significant Step 2: The influence of IKIF on LMX γ = 0.557*** p < 0.001 Significant Step 3: The influence of LMX on CWB γ = -0.174 p < 0.001 Significant Step 4: The influence of IKIF and LMX on CWB γ = -0.186 p < 0.001 Significant The first step is testing the influence of informational justice climate on CWB. This step is H2 testing and the result is not significant (γ = -0.052; SE = 0.053; p < 0.331). The second step is testing the influence of informational justice climate on LMX (H4), and the result is significantly positive (γ = 0.544; SE = 0.087; p < 0.001). The third step is testing the influence of LMX on CWB (H5) and the result is significantly negative (γ = -0.174; SE = 0.051; p < 0.001). The fourth step is testing informational justice climate on CWB and including LMX as mediating variable, and the result is significantly negative (γ = -0.186; p < 0.001). Therefore, H7 is supported, which means that LMX fully mediates the influence of informational justice climate on CWB [49]. V. DISCUSSION Although the results of this study do not support the research hypothesis, it supports other previous studies [50] that there is no significant influence of interpersonal and informational justice climate on CWB. The results of his study contradict the results from previous studies [15], [20], [29], [30], [51]. However, this result is relevant to the perspective of social exchange theory which uses rational assumption from economic science. According to this theory, in social relations, there are elements of reward, sacrifice (cost), and reciprocity that affect one another. This reciprocity can be in the form of good behavior (not counterproductive work behavior) for interpersonal justice that is perceived as a group. Researchers use social identity theory [52] which serves to strengthen the theory of social exchange. In this theory, cohesive group members can maintain a unity, and each group member should try to defend themselves to be part of their group. Social identity theory is used to explain that there are strong emotional ties, mutual evaluation, and close psychological relationships between members in cohesive groups [53]. In this cohesive group/work unit, positive interactions occur, so that they have a high level of trust and unity. Siswanti et al. / Journal of Southwest Jiaotong University / Vol.55 No.4 Aug. 2020 8 This mutual trust and togetherness is obtained from the social interaction of each group member/work unit, so that each member contributes to their coworkers and work groups [54] on positive behavior instead of negative behavior such as CWB. This result is quite reasonable since it is related to the theory of Attraction-Selection-Attrition (ASA) with its basic concept that individuals with similar characters will be attracted to, selected into, and retained in the same group. The ASA process raises homogeneity in organizations or groups/work units. The contribution of this theory is that interpersonal homogeneity tends to be formed in work group. The existence of homogeneity can lead to an agreement on the perception of justice climate [17], [30], [55], [56] which do not necessarily affect CWB directly. Other variables that might influence CWB from previous studies and the results of researchers’ interviews with respondents are: gender [57], [58]; personality [59]; self- awareness [60]; self-control [61]; emotional intelligence [62]; work condition, type of work, work partner, financial condition, work benefits [63], [64], [65]; social demography [66]; autonomy [67]; social support [68]; employee engagement [69]; individual characteristics [70]; stress level [71], [72], [73]; conflict [74]; organizational support [75]; emotion [68], [76]; self-efficacy [75]; self-esteem [78]; religiosity [79]; leadership [61], [80], [81]; and organizational culture [82]. The culture formed in the research object which was motivated by the founders/veterans formed a strong and collective adherence to the leader’s instructions. The test result of the cross-level influence of interpersonal justice climate on LMX shows a positive significant influence. This result supports previous studies [39], [50], [83], [84] which stated that procedural, distributive, and interactional justice has a positive significant relationship with LMX. According to [44], interpersonal justice shows the level of someone being treated well, respectfully, politely, and respected. The result of this study also support [86] who stated that interactional justice climate (interpersonal and informational) has a significant influence on LMX. In the perspective of social exchange theory [86], there is an element of reward for what has been obtained. Interpersonal justice climate that is perceived highly by the working groups will bring reward in the form of positive attitude towards the leader. This attitude can be in the form of ready to accept responsibility and/or ready to do a better job, as a form of increased quality of LMX, so that it leads to the in-group. The test result of the influence of LMX on CWB shows negative significant influence. This result supports previous studies [41], [42], [50], [87], [88], [89], [90], [91], which stated that in high quality LMX group, when leaders offer work that is broader in scope, responsibilities, communication, and support, members will respond with higher time, energy, responsibility, commitment, and reduce negative behavior as a return. The results of the data processing of the lecturers in the three new state universities showed a fairly high level of LMX, which means that the leader-member exchange relationship belongs to the in-group. According to [87], in high quality LMX group, when leaders offer work that is broader in scope, responsibilities, communication, and support, members will respond with higher time, energy, responsibility, and commitment as a return. This result is in accordance with the values embedded in these universities, especially the value of struggle. Struggle is the resilience in facing obstacles in the reality of life. The higher the resistance or resilience of leaders and members (through the process of LMX) in facing various challenges and obstacles of work in the organization, the lower the potential for doing things that harm the organization will be. The positive impact of the struggle in the LMX process thrive awareness of doing the best for the organization. The result of this study shows that LMX fully mediates the influence of interpersonal and informational justice climate on CWB. Collective perception about perceived interpersonal and informational justice will improve the quality of relationship between leaders and members. Respect and attention from leaders will raise the relationship between leaders and members to be based on trust and helping each other [92]. The treatment from leaders that respect their members has a direct influence on the decrease of counterproductive work behavior of the members [28], [41], [42], [50], [87], [89]. LMX in this study has a vital role since its existence can reduce counterproductive work behavior. VI. CONCLUSION The results of this study show that the interpersonal and informational justice climates do not have any influence on CWB, but both positively influence LMX, and LMX has a negative influence toward CWB. LMX fully mediates the influence of the interpersonal and informational justice climates toward CWB. The 9 results of this study deserve to be discussed further in future research, such as in a different scope and with an increase in the number of units, incorporating the moderating effects, or adding mediation chains to the research model. VII. LIMITATION 1. This study of the organizational justice climate (cross-level analysis) has been conducted in only three new state universities (PTNB) in Indonesia with a limited number of respondents, namely non-civil servant lecturers. Therefore, future research can be carried out in other state universities with both civil servant and non-civil servant lecturers as the respondents, as well as the staff. It can also be carried out in a service company or a manufacturing company, considering that the organizational justice climate is always interesting to study because of its impact on the positive and negative work behavior of employees. 2. The data in this study is gathered using a cross-sectional method. Future research will be much improved if it is done as a longitudinal study over a period of time, so that the consistency of respondents’ answers on the same variables and instruments can be known. REFERENCES [1] ROBINSON, S.L. and BENNET, R.J. (1995) A typology of deviant workplace behaviors: a multidimensional scaling study. Academy of Management Journal, 38 (20), pp. 555-572. [2] O’NEILL, T.A., LEWIS, R.J., and CARSWELL, J.J. (2011) Employee personality, justice perceptions, and the prediction of workplace deviance. Personality and Individual Differences, 51 (5), pp. 595-600. [3] FOX, S. and SPECTOR, P.E. (1999) A model of work frustration-aggression. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 20 (6), pp. 915-931. [4] GREENBERG, J. and BARLING, J. (1999) Predicting employee aggression against coworkers, subordinates and supervisors: The roles of person behaviors and perceive workplace factors. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 20, pp. 897-913. [5] VIGODA, E. (2002) Stress-related aftermaths to workplace politics: the relationships among politics, job distress, and aggressive behavior in organizations. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 23 (5), pp. 571- 591. [6] VARDI, Y. and WIENER, Y. (1996) Misbehavior in organizations: A motivational framework. Organization Science, 7 (2), pp. 151-165. [7] FOX, S., SPECTOR, P.E., and MILES, D. (2001) Counterproductive work behavior (CWB) in response to job stressors and organizational justice: some mediator and moderator tests for autonomy and emotions. Journal of Vocational Behavior, 59, pp. 291-309. [8] KLOTZ, A.C. and BUCKLEY, M.R. (2013) A historical perspective of counterproductive work behavior targeting the organization. Journal of Management History, 19 (1), pp. 114-132. [9] LE BLANC, M.M. and KELLOWAY, E.K. (2002) Predictors and outcomes of workplace violence and aggression. Journal of Applied Psychology, 87 (30), pp. 444-453. [10] PENNEY, L.M. and SPECTOR, P.E. (2005) Job stress, incivility, and counterproductive work behavior (CWB): The moderation role of negative affectivity. Jornal of Organizational Behavior, 26, pp. 777-796. [11] BENNET, R.J. and ROBINSON, S.L. (2000) Development of a measure of workplace deviance. Journal of Applied Psychology, 85 (3), pp. 349-360. [12] MURPHY, K.R. (1993) Honesty in the Workplace. Pacific Grove, California: Brooks/Cole. [13] KIRKMAN, B.L., JONES, R.G., and SHAPIRO, D.L. (2000) Why do employees resist teams? Examining the “resistance barrier” to work team effectiveness. International Journal of Conflict Management, 11 (1), pp. 74-92. [14] PHILLIPS, J.M., DOUTHITT, E.A., and HYLAND, M.M. (2001) The role of justice in team member satisfaction with the leader and attachment to the team. Journal of Applied Psychology, 86 (2), 316. [15] MOSSHOLDER, K.W., BENNETT, N., KEMERY, E.R., and WESOLOWSKI, M.A. (1998) Relationships between bases of power and work reactions: The mediational Siswanti et al. / Journal of Southwest Jiaotong University / Vol.55 No.4 Aug. 2020 10 role of procedural justice. Journal of Management, 24 (4), pp. 533-552. [16] NAUMANN, S.E. and BENNETT, N. (2000) A case for procedural justice climate: Development and test of a multilevel model. Academy of Management Journal, 43 (5), pp. 881-889. [17] SIMONS, T. and ROBERSON, Q. (2003) Why managers should care about fairness: the effects of aggregate justice perceptions on organizational outcomes. Journal of Applied Psychology, 88 (3), 432. [18] LI, A. and CROPANZANO, R. (2009) Fairness at the group level: Justice climate and intraunit justice climate. Journal of Management, 35 (3), pp. 564-599. [19] EHRHART, M.G. (2004) Leadership and procedural justice climate as antecedents of unit-level organizational citizenship behavior. Personnel Psychology, 57 (1), pp. 61-94. [20] ROBERSON, Q.M. and COLQUITT, J.A. (2005) Shared and configural justice: A social network model of justice in teams. Academy of Management Review, 30 (3), pp. 595-607. [21] LAVELLE, J.J., RUPP, D.E., and BROCKNER, J. (2007) Taking a multifoci approach to the study of justice, social exchange, and citizenship behavior: The target similarity model. Journal of Management, 33 (6), pp. 841-866. [22] ZAPATA-PHELAN, C.P., COLQUITT, J.A., SCOTT, B.A., and LIVINGSTON, B. (2009) Procedural justice, interactional justice, and task performance: The mediating role of intrinsic motivation. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 108 (1), pp. 93-105. [23] GREENBERG, J. (1993) Justice and organizational citizenship: A commentary on the state of the science. Employee Responsibilities and Rights Journal, 6 (3), pp. 249-256. [24] COLQUITT, J.A., CONLON, D.E., WESSON, M.J., PORTER, C.O., and NG, K.Y. (2001) Justice at the millennium: a meta-analytic review of 25 years of organizational justice research. Journal of Applied Psychology, 86 (3), pp. 425-445. [25] PENNEY, L.M. and SPECTOR, P.E. (2002) Narcissism and counterproductive work behavior: Do bigger egos mean bigger problems? International Journal of selection and Assessment, 10 (1-2), pp. 126-134. [26] GRUYS, M.L. and SACKETT, P.R. (2003) Investigating the dimensionality of counterproductive work behavior. International Journal of Selection and Assessment, 11 (1), pp. 30-42. [27] DEVONISH, D. and GREENIDGE, D. (2010) The effect of organizational justice on contextual performance, counterproductive work behaviors, and task performance: Investigating the moderating role of ability-based emotional intelligence. International Journal of Selection and Assessment, 18 (1), pp. 75-86. [28] AKREMI, A.E., VANDENBERGHE, C., and CAMERMAN, J. (2010) The role of justice and social exchange relationships in workplace deviance: Test of mediated model. Human Relations, 63 (11), pp. 1687-1717. [29] SPELL, C.S. and ARNOLD, T.J. (2007) A multi-level analysis of organizational justice climate, structure, and employee mental health. Journal of Management, 33 (5), pp. 724-751. [30] LIAO, H. and RUPP, D.E. (2005) The impact of justice climate and justice orientation on work outcomes: a cross-level multifoci framework. Journal of Applied Psychology, 90 (2), 242. [31] AQUINO, K., LEWIS, M.U., and BRADFIELD, M. (1999) Justice constructs, negative affectivity, and employee deviance: A proposed model and empirical test. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 20 (7), pp. 1073-1091. [32] GRAEN, G.B. and UHL-BIEN, M. (1995) Relationship-based approach to leadership: Development of leader-member exchange (LMX) theory of leadership over 25 years: Applying a multi-level multi- domain perspective. The Leadership Quarterly, 6, pp. 219-247. [33] LIDEN, R.C., SPARROWE, R.T., and WAYNE, S.J. (1997) Leader-member exchange theory: The past and potential for the future. Research in Personnel and Human Resources Management, 15, pp. 47- 120. [34] VAN BREUKELEN, W., VAN DER LEEDEN, R., WESSELIUS, W., and HOES, 11 M. (2012) Differential treatment within sports teams, leader–member (coach–player) exchange quality, team atmosphere, and team performance. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 33 (1), pp. 43-63. [35] GRAEN, G.B. and SCANDURA, T.A. (1987) Toward a psychology of dyadic organizing. Research in Organizational Behavior, 9, pp. 175-208. [36] TRUCKENBRODT, Y.B. (2001) An empirical assessment of the relationship between leader-member exchange and organizational commitment and organizational citizenship behavior. Doctoral thesis. [37] RASOULI, R. and HAGHTAALI, M. (2009) Impact of Leader-Member Exchange on Job Satisfaction in Tehran Social Security Branches. Turkish Public Administration Annual, pp. 32-35. [38] LEE, H., MURRMANN, S.K., MURRMANN, K.F., and KIM, K. (2010) Organizational justice as a mediator of the relationships between leader-member exchange and employees’ turnover intentions. Journal of Hospitality Marketing & Management, 19 (4), pp. 97-114. [39] BURTON, J.P., SABLYNSKI, C.J., and SEKIGUCHI, T. (2008) Linking justice, performance, and citizenship via leader– member exchange. Journal of Business and Psychology, 23 (1-2), pp. 51-61. [40] PICCOLO, R.F., BARDES, M., MAYER, D.M., and JUDGE, T.A. (2008) Does high quality leader–member exchange accentuate the effects of organizational justice? European Journal of Work and Organizational Psychology, 17 (2), pp. 273- 298. [41] ERDOGAN, B. and LIDEN, R.C. (2006) Collectivism as a moderator of responses to organizational justice: implications for leader-member exchange and ingratiation. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 27 (1), pp. 1-17. [42] VIDYARTHI, P.R., LIDEN, R.C., ANAND, S., ERDOGAN, B., and GHOSH, S. (2010) Where doI stand? Examining eteh effects of leader-member exchange social comparison on employee work behaviors. Journal of Applied Psychology, 95 (5), pp. 849-861. [43] SCHYNS, B., KROON, B., and MOORS, G. (2008) Follower characteristics and the perception of leader-member exchange. Journal of Managerial Psychology, 23 (7), pp. 772-788. [44] COLQUITT, J.A. (2001) On the dimensionality of organizational justice: A construct validation of a measure. Journal of Applied Psychology, 86 (3), pp. 386-400. [45] HAIR, J.F., BLACK, W.C., BABIN, B.J., ANDERSON, R.E., and TATHAM, R.L. (2006) Multivariate Data Analysis, Vol. 6. New Delhi: Pearson Education. [46] RAUDENBUSH, S.W. and BRYK, A.S. (2002) Hierarchical Linear Models: Applications and Data Analysis Methods. 2nd ed. Newbury Park, California: Sage. [47] SISWANTI, Y., TJAHJONO, H.K., HARTONO, A., and PRAJOGO, W. (2020) Organizational Justice Climate: Construct Measurement and Validation. Test Engineering and Management, 82, pp. 8574- 8590. [48] NEWMAN, D.A. and SIN, H.P. (2009) How do missing data bias estimates of within-group agreement? Sensitivity of SD WG, CVWG, rWG (J), rWG (J)*, and ICC to systematic nonresponse. Organizational Research Methods, 12 (1), pp. 113-147. [49] MACKINNON, D.P. and LUECKEN, L.J. (2008) How and for whom? Mediation and moderation in health psychology. Health Psychology, 27 (2S), pp. S99-S100. [50] COLQUITT, J.A., RODELL, J.B., ZAPATA, C.P., SCOTT, B.A., LONG, D.M., and CONLON, D.E. (2013) Justice at the millenium, a decade later: a meta analytic test of social exchange and affect-based perspectives. Journal of Applied Psychology, 96 (2), pp. 199-236. [51] COHEN-CHARASH, Y. and SPECTOR, P.E. (2001) The role of justice in organizations: a meta-analysis. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 86 (2), pp. 278-321. [52] STETS, J.E. and BURKE, P.J. (2000) Identity theory and social identity theory. Social Psychology Quarterly, 63, pp. 224- 237. [53] TURNER, J.C., MICHAEL, A.H., PENELOPE, J.O., STEPHEN, D.R., and MARGARET, S.W. (1987) Rediscovering Siswanti et al. / Journal of Southwest Jiaotong University / Vol.55 No.4 Aug. 2020 12 the Social Group: A Self-Categorization Theory. New York: Brasil Blackwell. [54] MAN, D.C. and LAM, S.S. (2003) The effects of job complexity and autonomy on cohesiveness in collectivistic and individualistic work groups: a cross-cultural analysis. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 24 (8), pp. 979-1001. [55] COLQUITT, J.A., NOE, R.A., and JACKSON, C.L. (2002) Justice in teams: Antecedents and consequences of procedural justice climate. Personnel Psychology, 55 (1), pp. 83-109. [56] TANGIRALA, S. and RAMUNUJAM, R. (2008) Employee silence on critical work issues: The cross level effects of procedural justice climate. Personnel Psychology, 61, 37068. [57] CHERNYAK-HAI, L. and TZINER, A. (2014) Relationships between counterproductive work behavior, perceived justice and climate, occupational status, and leader-member exchange. Journal of Work and Organizational Psychology, 30 (1), pp. 1-12. [58] SANTOS, A. and EGER, A. (2014) Gender differences and predictors of workplace deviance behaviour: the role of job stress, job satisfaction and personality on interpersonal and organisational deviance. International Journal of Management Practice, 7 (1), pp. 19-38. [59] VAN ZYL, C.J.J. and DE BRUIN, G.P. (2018) Predicting counterproductive work behavior with narrow personality traits: A nuanced examination using quantile regression. Personality and Individual Differences, 131, pp. 45-50. [60] JACOBSON, K.J.L. (2009) Contextual and Individual Predictors of Counterproductive Work Behaviors. Tempe, Arizona: Arizona State University. [61] JU, D., XU, M., QIN, X., and SPECTOR, P. (2019) A Multilevel Study of Abusive Supervision, Norms, and Personal Control on Counterproductive Work Behavior: A Theory of Planned Behavior Approach. Journal of Leadership & Organizational Studies, 26 (2), pp. 163-178. [62] MIAO, C., HUMPHREY, R.H., & QIAN, S. (2017) Are the emotionally intelligent good citizens or counterproductive? A meta-analysis of emotional intelligence and its relationships with organizational citizenship behavior and counterproductive work behavior. Personality and Individual Differences, 116, pp. 144-156. [63] FAGBOHUNGBE, B.O., AKINBODE, G.A., and AYODEJI, F. (2012) Organizational determinants of workplace deviant behaviours: An empirical analysis in Nigeria. International Journal of Business and Management, 7 (5), 207. [64] DEBUSSCHER, J., HOFMANS, J., and DE FRUYT, F. (2016) The effect of state core self-evaluations on task performance, organizational citizenship behaviour, and counterproductive work behaviour. European Journal of Work and Organizational Psychology, 25 (2), pp. 301-315. [65] RAHIM, A.R., SHABUDIN, A., and MOHD NASURDIN, A. (2012) Effects of job characteristics on counterproductive work behavior among production employees: Malaysian experience. International Journal of Business and Development Studies, 8 (1), pp. 117-139. [66] UCHE, I.I., GEORGE, O., and ABIOLA, W. (2017) Counterproductive work behaviors: a socio-demographic characteristic-based study among employees in the Nigerian maritime sector. Acta Universitatis Sapientiae, Economics and Business, 5 (1), pp. 117-138. [67] TUCKER, J.S., SINCLAIR, R.R., MOHR, C.D., ADLER, A.B., THOMAS, J.L., and SALVI, A.D. (2009) Stress and counterproductive work behavior: Multiple relationships between demands, control, and soldier indiscipline over time. Journal of Occupational Health Psychology, 14 (3), 257. [68] MATTA, F.K., EROL-KORKMAZ, H.T., JOHNSON, R.E., and BIÇAKSIZ, P. (2014) Significant work events and counterproductive work behavior: The role of fairness, emotions, and emotion regulation. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 35 (7), pp. 920-944. [69] ARIANI, D.W. (2013) The relationship between employee engagement, organizational citizenship behavior, and counterproductive work behavior. 13 International Journal of Business Administration, 4 (2), 46. [70] LUCAS, G.M. and FRIEDRICH, J. (2005) Individual differences in workplace deviance and integrity as predictors of academic dishonesty. Ethics & Behavior, 15 (1), pp. 15-35. [71] HASANATI, N., WINARSUNU, T., and KARINA, V.D. (2018) The influence of interpersonal conflict on counterproductive work behaviour mediated by job stress. In: Proceedings of the 3rd ASEAN Conference on Psychology, Counselling, and Humanities. Atlantis Press, pp. 276-282. [72] MAHDI, S., IBRAHIM, M., and ARMIA, S. (2018) The Role of Negative Emotions on the Relationship of Job Stress and Counterproductive Work Behavior (Research on Public Senior High School Teachers). International Journal of Asian Social Science, 8 (2), pp. 77-84. [73] DE CLERCQ, D., HAQ, I.U., and AZEEM, M.U. (2019) Time-related work stress and counterproductive work behavior: Invigorating roles of deviant personality traits. Personnel Review, 48 (7), pp. 1756- 1781. [74] ZHAO, J., XIAO, S., MAO, J., and LIU, W. (2018) The buffering effect of Machiavellianism on the relationship between role conflict and counterproductive work behavior. Frontiers in Psychology, 9, 1776. [75] VATANKHAH, S., JAVID, E., and RAOOFI, A. (2017) Perceived organizational support as the mediator of the relationships between high-performance work practices and counter-productive work behavior: Evidence from airline industry. Journal of Air Transport Management, 59, pp. 107-115. [76] HAROLD, C.M., OH, I.S., HOLTZ, B.C., HAN, S., and GIACALONE, R.A. (2016) Fit and frustration as drivers of targeted counterproductive work behaviors: A multifoci perspective. Journal of Applied Psychology, 101 (11), pp. 1513-1535. [77] WIDYANTI, R., IRHAMNI, G., RATNA, S., and BASUKI. (2020) Organizational Justice and Organizational Pride to Achieve Job Satisfaction and Job Performance. Journal of Southwest Jiaotong University, 55 (3). Available from http://jsju.org/index.php/journal/article/view/ 637. [78] WHELPLEY, C.E. and MCDANIEL, M.A. (2016) Self-esteem and counterproductive work behaviors: a systematic review. Journal of Managerial Psychology, 31 (4), pp. 850-863. [79] PALUPI, M. and TJAHJONO, H.K. (2016) A model of religiousity and organizational justice: the impact on commitment and dysfunctional behavior. In: Proceedings of the 27th International Business Information Management Association Conference, Milan, May 2016. King of Prussia, Pennsylvania: IBIMA Publishing. [80] PUNI, A., AGYEMANG, C.B., and ASAMOAH, E.S. (2016) Leadership styles, employee turnover intentions and counterproductive work behaviours. International Journal of Innovative Research and Development, 5 (1), pp. 1-7. [81] HSI, E. (2017) An Examination of Predictors of Counterproductive Work Behaviors: Personality Traits and Transformational Leadership. [82] O'BOYLE, E.H.,JR., FORSYTH, D.R., BANKS, G.C., and MCDANIEL, M.A. (2012) A meta-analysis of the Dark Triadand work behavior: A social exchange perspective. Journal of Applied Psychology, 97, pp. 557-579. [83] CROPANZANO, R., PREHAR, C.A., and CHEN, P.Y. (2002) Using social exchange theory to distinguish procedural from interactional justice. Group & Organization Management, 27 (3), pp. 324- 351. [84] WILLIAMS, E.A., SCANDURA, T.A., PISSARIS, S., and WOODS, J.M. (2016) Justice perceptions, leader-member exchange, and upward influence tactics. Leadership & Organization Development Journal, 37 (7), pp. 1000-1015. [85] FEIN, E.C., TZINER, A., LUSKY, L., and PALACHY, O. (2013) Relationships between ethical climate, justice perceptions, and LMX. Leadership and Organization Development Journal, 34 (2), pp. 147-163. [86] COOK, K.S. and RICE, E. (2006) Social Exchange Theory. In: DELAMATER, J. (ed.) Handbook of Social Psychology. http://jsju.org/index.php/journal/article/view/637 http://jsju.org/index.php/journal/article/view/637 Siswanti et al. / Journal of Southwest Jiaotong University / Vol.55 No.4 Aug. 2020 14 Handbooks of Sociology and Social Research. Boston, Massachusetts: Springer, pp. 53-76. [87] DANSEREAU, F., GRAEN, G.B., and HAGA, W.J. (1975) A vertical dyad linkage approach to leadership within formal organizations: A longitudinal investigation of the role making process. Organizational Behavior & Human Performance, 13, pp. 46- 78. [88] PILLAI, R., SCANDURA, T.A., and WILLIAMS, E.A. (1999) Leadership and organizational justice: Similarities and differences across cultures. Journal of International Business Studies, 30 (4), pp. 763-779. [89] SCHYNS, B., MEINDL, J.R., and CROON, M.A. (2007) The romance of leadership scale: Cross-cultural testing and refinement. Leadership, 3 (1), pp. 29-46. [90] KELLOWAY, E.K., FRANCIS, L., PROSSER, M., and CAMERON, J.E. (2010) Counterproductive work behavior as protest. Human Resource Management Review, 20 (1), pp. 18-25. [91] CLARK, S.B. (2013) Understanding Counterproductive Work Behavior: Aggressive Employees' Responses to Leader- Member Exchange. Master thesis, East Carolina University. [92] LIDEN, R.C., WAYNE, S.J., and STILWELL, D. (1993) A longitudinal study on the early development of leader-member exchanges. Journal of Applied Psychology, 78 (4), 662. 参考文: [1] ROBINSON,S.L. 和 BENNET,R.J. (1995)异常工作场所行为的类型学:多 维尺度研究。管理学院学报,38(20), 第 555-572 页。 [2] T.A. O'NEILL,R.J 。 LEWIS, 和 J.J. CARSWELL。(2011)员工个性,正义 感以及对工作场所偏差的预测。人格与个 体差异,51(5),第 595-600 页。 [3] S. FOX 和 P.E. SPECTOR。(1999)工 作挫折侵略模型。组织行为学杂志,20 (6),第 915-931 页。 [4] GREENBERG , J. 和 BARLING , J. (1999)预测员工对同事,下属和主管的 侵略:人的行为和感知工作场所因素的作 用。组织行为杂志,20,第 897-913 页。 [5] VIGODA,E.(2002)与工作场所政治 相关的压力后果:政治,工作压力和组织 中的攻击行为之间的关系。组织行为学杂 志,23(5),第 571-591 页。 [6] VARDI,Y. 和 WIENER,Y.(1996) 组织中的不当行为:动机框架。组织科学, 7 (2),第 151-165 页。 [7] S. FOX , S. SPECTOR , P.E., 和 MILES,D.(2001)为应对工作压力和组 织公正而产生的适得其反的工作行为 (CWB):对自主性和情绪的一些调解人 和主持人测试。职业行为杂志,59,第 291-309 页。 [8] A.C. KLOTZ 和 M.R. BUCKLEY (2013)针对组织的适得其反的工作行为 的历史观点。管理历史杂志,19(1), 第 114-132 页。 [9] LE BLANC , M.M. 和 英 国 的 KELLOWAY(2002)工作场所暴力和侵 略的预测因素和结果。应用心理学杂志, 87(30),第 444-453 页。 [10] 彭尼( LEN )和 SPECTOR ( PE ) (2005)工作压力,不活跃,和适得其反 的工作行为(CWB):负面影响的调节作 用。组织行为研究杂志,26,第 777-796 页。 [11] BENNET,R.J。和 ROBINSON,S.L. (2000)开发了一种衡量工作场所偏差的 方法。应用心理学杂志,85( 3),第 349-360 页。 [12] MURPHY,K.R。(1993)在工作场 所诚实。加利福尼亚太平洋丛林镇:布鲁 克斯/科尔。 [13] B.L. KIRKMAN,R.G。琼斯, 和 D.L. SHAPIRO。(2000)为什么员工抵制团 队?检查工作团队效率的“阻力壁垒”。国 际冲突管理杂志,11 (1),第 74-92 页。 [14] PHILLIPS,J.M.,E.A。DOUTHITT, 和 M.M. HYLAND(2001)正义在团队成 员对领导者的满意和对团队的依恋中的作 用。应用心理学杂志,86(2),316。 [15] MOSSHOLDER , K.W. , BENNETT , N.,KEMERY,E.R., 和 WESOLOWSKI, 15 M.A.(1998)权力基础与工作反应之间的 关系:程序正义的中介作用。管理杂志, 24(4),第 533-552 页。 [16] NAUMANN,S.E. 和 BENNETT,N. (2000)程序正义环境的案例:多层次模 型的开发和检验。管理学院学报, 43 (5),第 881-889 页。 [17] SIMONS , T. 和 ROBERSON , Q. (2003)为什么管理者应该关注公平:总 体正义观念对组织结果的影响。应用心理 学杂志,88(3),432。 [18] LI , A. 和 CROPANZANO , R. (2009)团体层面的公平:正义气氛和单 位内部正义气氛。管理学报,35(3), 第 564-599 页。 [19] EHRHART,医学硕士(2004)领导 力和程序正义氛围是单位级别组织公民行 为的前提。人事心理学,57(1),第 61- 94 页。 [20] 罗伯逊,Q.M。和 COLQUITT,J.A. (2005)共享和配置正义:团队正义的社 交网络模型。管理评论学会,30(3), 第 595-607 页。 [21] LAVELLE , J.J. , RUPP , D.E., 和 BROCKNER,J.(2007)采用多焦点方法 研究正义,社会交流和公民行为:目标相 似性模型。管理学报,33(6),第 841- 866 页。 [22] ZAPATA-PHELAN , C.P. , COLQUITT , J.A. , SCOTT , B.A., 和 LIVINGSTON,B.(2009)程序正义,互 动正义和任务执行:内在动机的中介作用。 组织行为与人类决策过程,108(1),第 93-105 页。 [23] GREENBERG,J。(1993)正义与组 织公民权:对科学状态的评论。员工责任 与权利杂志,6(3),第 249-256 页。 [24] J.A. 的 COLQUITT , D.E 。 的 CONLON,M.J。的 WESSON,C.O。的 PORTER, 和 K.Y.的 NG。(2001)千年司 法:对 25 年组织正义研究的荟萃分析。 应用心理学杂志,86(3),第 425-445 页。 [25] 彭尼( LEN )和 SPECTOR ( PE ) (2002)自恋和适得其反的工作行为:更 大的自我意味着更大的问题吗?国际选择 与评估杂志,10(1-2),第 126-134 页。 [26] GRUYS,M.L. 和 SACKETT,P.R. (2003)调查适得其反的工作行为的维度。 国际选择与评估杂志,11(1),第 30-42 页。 [27] DEVONISH,D. 和 GREENIDGE,D. (2010)组织公正对情境绩效,适得其反 的工作行为和任务绩效的影响:调查基于 能力的情商的调节作用。国际选择与评估 杂志,18(1),第 75-86 页。 [28] AKREMI,A.E.,VANDENBERGHE, C., 和 CAMERMAN,J.(2010)司法和社 会交换关系在工作场所偏差中的作用:中 介模型的检验。人际关系, 63(11),第 1687-1717 页。 [29] SPELL,C.S。和 ARNOLD,T.J。 (2007)对组织公正的气候,结构和员工 心理健康进行了多层次分析。管理学报, 33(5),第 724-751 页。 [30] LIAO,H。和 RUPP,D.E.(2005) 司法环境和司法方向对工作成果的影响: 跨层次的多焦点框架。应用心理学杂志, 90(2),242。 [31] AQUINO , K. , LEWIS , M.U., 和 BRADFIELD,M.(1999)正义建构,消 极情感和员工偏差:提议的模型和实证检 验。组织行为学杂志,20(7),第 1073- 1091 页。 [32] GRAEN , G.B. 和 UHL-BIEN , M. (1995)基于关系的领导方法:领导者- 成员交换(LMX)领导理论在 25 年间的 发展:应用多层次,多领域的观点。领导 力季刊,6,第 219-247 页。 [33] R.C. LIDEN,R.T。SPARROWE, 和 S.J. WAYNE。(1997)领导者-成员交 换理论:过去和未来的潜力。人事与人力 资源管理研究,15,第 47-120 页。 [34] W. VAN BREUKELEN , R 。 VAN DER LEEDEN,W。WESSELIUS, 和 M. HOES(2012)运动队内部的差别待遇, 领导-成员(教练-球员)的交换素质,团 队氛围和团队绩效。组织行为学杂志,33 (1),第 43-63 页。 Siswanti et al. / Journal of Southwest Jiaotong University / Vol.55 No.4 Aug. 2020 16 [35] GRAEN,GB 以及 SCANDURA,T.A. (1987)走向二元化组织心理学。组织行 为研究,9,第 175-208 页。 [36] TRUCKENBRODT,Y.B。(2001) 对领导者-成员交换与组织承诺和组织公 民行为之间关系的实证评估。博士论文。 [37] RASOULI,R. 和 HAGHTAALI,M. (2009)领导成员交流对德黑兰社会保障 部门工作满意度的影响。土耳其公共管理 年度刊,第 32-35 页。 [38] LEE, H.,S.K。MURRMANN,K.F。 MURRMANN, 和 K. KIM(2010)组织正 义,作为领导者与员工交换与员工离职意 图之间关系的中介。酒店营销与管理杂志, 19(4),第 97-114 页。 [39] BURTON,J.P.,C.J。SABLYNSKI, 和 T. SEKIGUCHI(2008)通过领导人与 成员之间的交流将正义,绩效和公民身份 联系起来。商业与心理学杂志,23(1- 2),第 51-61 页。 [40] PICCOLO , R.F. , BARDES , M. , Mayer,D.M., 和 JUDGE,T.A.(2008) 高素质的领导-成员交流是否会增强组织 公正的影响? 欧洲工作与组织心理学杂志, 17 (2),第 273-298 页。 [41] B. ERDOGAN 和 R.C. LIDEN 。 (2006)集体主义作为对组织正义的回应 的调解者:对领导成员交流和敬畏的影响。 组织行为学杂志,27(1),第 1-17 页。 [42] VIDYARTHI,P.R.,LIDEN,R.C., ANAND , S. , ERDOGAN , B., 和 GHOSH,S.(2010)我站在哪里?检查领 导者-成员交换社会比较对员工工作行为 的影响。应用心理学杂志,95(5),第 849-861 页。 [43] SCHYNS , B. , KROON , B., 和 MOORS,G.(2008)追随者特征和领导 者与成员之间的交流感。管理心理学杂志, 23(7),第 772-788 页。 [44] COLQUITT,J.A。(2001)关于组织 正义的维度:一种措施的结构验证。应用 心理学杂志,86(3),第 386-400 页。 [45] HAIR , J.F. , BLACK , W.C. , BABIN , B.J. , ANDERSON , R.E., 和 TATHAM,R.L.(2006)多元数据分析, 卷。6。新德里:培生教育。 [46] RAUDENBUSH,S.W.以及 BRYK, A.S.(2002)分层线性模型:应用程序和 数据分析方法。第二版。加利福尼亚纽伯 里公园:圣人。 [47] SISWANTI,Y.,TJAHJONO,H.K., HARTONO , A 。 和 PRAJOGO , W 。 (2020)组织正义的气候:构建度量和验 证。测试工程与管理,82,第 8574-8590 页。 [48] 纽曼,D.A。和 SIN,H.P.(2009)缺 失数据如何使集团内部协议的估计偏倚? 工作组,工作组,工作量(J),工作组 (J)*和国际刑事法院对系统无响应的敏 感性。组织研究方法,12 (1),第 113-147 页。 [49] MACKINNON,D.P。和 LUECKEN, L.J.(2008)如何以及为谁服务?健康心 理学的调解和节制。健康心理学, 27 (2S),第 S99-S100 页。 [50] J.A. COLQUITT , J.B 。 RODELL , ZAPATA,C.P。SCOTT,B.A。SCOTT, LONG D.M., 和 D.E. CONLON。(2013) 十年后的千年正义:对社会交流和基于情 感的观点的荟萃分析。应用心理学杂志, 96(2),第 199-236 页。 [51] Y. COHEN-CHARASH 和 P.E. SPECTOR ( 2001 ) 正义在组织中 的 作 用:荟萃分析。组织行为与人类决策过程, 86 (2),第 278-321 页。 [52] STETS , J.E 。 和 BURKE , P.J 。 (2000)身份理论和社会身份理论。社会 心理学季刊,63,第 224-237 页。 [53] 特纳(J.C.),迈克尔(A.H.),佩 内洛普(PENELOPE),乔布斯(D.R.), 和 马格瑞特(S.W.)(1987)重新发现社 会群体:一种自我分类理论。纽约:巴西 布莱克威尔。 [54] 哥伦比亚特区曼彻斯特大学 和 林圣 美学院(2003)工作复杂性和自主性对集 体和个人主义工作组凝聚力的影响:跨文 化分析。组织行为学杂志,24(8), 第 979-1001 页。 17 [55] J.A. COLQUITT,R.A。NOE, 和 C.L. JACKSON。(2002)团队正义:程序正 义氛围的前因和后果。人事心理学,55 (1),第 83-109 页。 [56] TANGIRALA,S. 和 RAMUNUJAM, R.(2008)员工在关键工作问题上保持沉 默:程序正义气氛的跨层次影响。人事心 理学,61,37068。 [57] CHERNYAK-HAI,L. 和 TZINER,A. (2014)适得其反的工作行为,正义感与 气候,职业地位以及领导者与成员之间的 关系。工作与组织心理学杂志, 30(1), 第 1-12 页。 [58] SANTOS,A. 和 EGER,A.(2014) 性别差异和工作场所偏差行为的预测指 标:工作压力,工作满意度和个性在人际 和组织偏差方面的作用。国际管理实践杂 志,7(1),第 19-38 页。 [59] VAN ZYL,C.J.J。和 DE BRUIN, G.P.(2018)用狭窄的人格特质预测适得 其反的工作行为:使用分位数回归的细微 差别检查。人格与个体差异,131,第 45- 50 页。 [60] 雅各布森,K.J.L。(2009)反生产工 作行为的情境和个体预测。亚利桑那州坦 佩:亚利桑那州立大学。 [61] JU , D. , XU , M. , QIN , X., 和 SPECTOR,P.(2019)对适得其反的工作 行为的滥用监督,规范和个人控制的多层 次研究:计划行为方法理论。领导与组织 研究杂志,26(2),第 163-178 页。 [62] MIAO,C.,HUMPHREY,R.H., 和 QIAN,S.(2017)情绪智力好的好公民还 是适得其反?对情绪智力及其与组织公民 行为和适得其反的工作行为之间关系的元 分析。人格与个体差异,116,第 144-156 页。 [63] FAGBOHUNGUNG , B.O. , AKINBODE , G.A., 和 AYODEJI , F. (2012)工作场所越轨行为的组织决定因 素:尼日利亚的一项经验分析。国际商业 与管理杂志,7(5),207。 [64] DEBUSSCHER,J.,HOFMANS,J., 和 DE FRUYT,F.(2016)国家核心自我 评估对任务绩效,组织公民行为和适得其 反的工作行为的影响。欧洲工作与组织心 理学杂志,25(2),第 301-315 页。 [65] RAHIM,A.R.,SHABUDIN,A., 和 MOHD NASURDIN,A.(2012)工作特 征对生产员工中适得其反的工作行为的影 响:马来西亚的经验。国际商业与发展研 究杂志,8(1),第 117-139 页。 [66] UCHE , I.I. , GEORGE , O 。 和 ABIOLA,W。(2017)适得其反的工作 行为:一项基于尼日利亚尼日利亚海事部 门雇员的社会人口学特征的研究。大学学 报,经济学和商业,5(1),第 117-138 页。 [67] TUCKER,J.S.,SINCLAIR,R.R., MOHR , C.D. , ADLER , A.B. , THOMAS , J.L 。 和 SALVI , A.D 。 (2009)压力和适得其反的工作行为:随 着时间的流逝,需求,控制和士兵纪律之 间的多重关系。职业健康心理学杂志,14 (3),257。 [68] F.K. MATTA , H.T 。 EROL- KORKMAZ , R.E 。 JOHNSON, 和 P. BIÇAKSIZ(2014)重要的工作事件和适 得其反的工作行为:公平,情绪和情绪调 节的作用。组织行为学杂志,35(7), 第 920-944 页。 [69] ARIANI,D.W。(2013)员工敬业 度,组织公民行为和适得其反的工作行为 之间的关系。国际工商管理杂志,4(2), 46。 [70] LUCAS,G.M。和 FRIEDRICH,J. (2005)工作场所偏差和诚信的个体差异 是学术不诚实的预测因素。道德与行为, 15(1),第 15-35 页。 [71] N. HASANATI , T 。 WINARSUNU, 和 V.D. KARINA。(2018)人际冲突对 工作压力介导的适得其反的工作行为的影 响。在:第三届东盟心理学,咨询和人文 会议论文集。亚特兰蒂斯出版社,第 276- 282 页。 [72] MAHDI , S. , IBRAHIM , M., 和 ARMIA,S.(2018)负面情绪在工作压力 与适得其反的工作行为之间的关系(对公 立高中教师的研究)。国际亚洲社会科学 杂志,8(2),第 77-84 页。 Siswanti et al. / Journal of Southwest Jiaotong University / Vol.55 No.4 Aug. 2020 18 [73] DE CLERCQ , D. , HAQ , I.U., 和 AZEEM,M.U.(2019)与时间相关的工 作压力和适得其反的工作行为:激发人格 特质的作用。人事评论,48( 7),第 1756-1781 页。 [74] 赵剑,肖南,毛剑,刘维。(2018) 马基雅维利主义对角色冲突和适得其反的 工作行为之间关系的缓冲作用。心理学前 沿,1776 年 9 月。 [75] S. VATANKHAH,E。JAVID, 和 A. RAOOFI(2017)将组织支持视为高性能 工作实践与适得其反的工作行为之间关系 的中介者:来自航空业的证据。航空运输 管理杂志,59,第 107-115 页。 [76] HAROLD,C.M.,OH,I.S.,HOLTZ, B.C.,HAN,S.,和 GIACALONE,R.A. (2016)适应和挫折感成为有针对性的适 得其反的工作行为的驱动力:多焦点视角。 应用心理学杂志,101(11),第 1513- 1535 页。 [77] R. WIDYANTI , G 。 IRHAMNI , RATNA,S。和 BASUKI。(2020)实现 工作满意度和工作绩效的组织正义和组织 自豪感。西南交通大学学报,55(3)。 可 从 http://jsju.org/index.php/journal/article/view/ 637 获得。 [78] WHELPLEY,C.E. 和 MCDANIEL, M.A.(2016)自尊和适得其反的工作行 为:系统评价。管理心理学杂志,31 (4), 第 850-863 页。 [79] M. PALUPI 和 H.K. TJAHJONO 。 (2016)宗教和组织公正的模型:对承诺 和功能失调行为的影响。在:第 27 届国 际商业信息管理协会会议记录,2016 年 5 月,米兰。宾夕法尼亚州普鲁士国王:伊 比马出版。 [80] A. PUNI,C.B。AGYEMANG, 和 E.S. ASAMOAH。(2016)领导风格,员工离 职意图和适得其反的工作行为。国际创新 研究与发展杂志,5(1),第 1-7 页。 [81] HSI,E.(2017)对适得其反的工作 行为的预测因素的检验:人格特质和变革 型领导。 [82] O'BOYLE,E.H.,JR。,FORSYTH, D.R.,BANKS,G.C., 和 MCDANIEL, M.A.(2012)对“黑暗三合会”工作行为的 荟萃分析:一种社会交流的观点。应用心 理学杂志,97,第 557-579 页。 [83] CROPANZANO , R. , PREHAR , C.A., 和 CHEN,P.Y.(2002)使用社会交 换理论来区分程序和互动正义。小组与组 织管理,27(3),第 324-351 页。 [84] E.A.威廉姆斯,TA.A。SCANDURA, S。PISSARIS, 和 J.M. WOODS(2016)正 义感,领导者-成员交流和向上影响策略。 领导力与组织发展杂志 , 37 ( 7 ),第 1000-1015 页。 [85] E.C. FEIN , A 。 TZINER , L 。 LUSKY, 和 O. PALACHY(2013)道德氛 围,正义观念和 LMX 之间的关系。领导 力与组织发展杂志,34 (2),第 147-163 页。 [86] COOK,K.S。和 RICE,E.(2006) 社会交流理论。在:德拉马特,J。(编 辑)社会心理学手册。社会学和社会研究 手册。马萨诸塞州波士顿:施普林格,第 53-76 页。 [87] DANSEREAU,F.,GRAEN,G.B., 和 HAGA,W.J.(1975)在正式组织中领 导层的垂直双联方法:对角色形成过程的 纵向调查。组织行为与人类绩效,13,第 46-78 页。 [88] R. PILLAI , T.A 。 SCANDURA, 和 E.A. WILLIAMS。(1999)领导力与组织 公正:跨文化的异同。国际商业研究杂志, 30(4),第 763-779 页。 [89] SCHYNS , B. , MEINDL , J.R., 和 CROON , M.A. ( 2007 )领导规模的浪 漫:跨文化的测试和完善。领导力,3 (1),第 29-46 页。 [90] E.K. KELLOWAY,L。FRANCIS, M 。 PROSSER, 和 J.E. CAMERON (2010)以示反效果的工作行为作为抗议。 人力资源管理评论,20(1),第 18-25 页。 [91] CLARK,S.B.(2013)了解适得其反 的工作行为:积极进取的员工对领导成员 交换的反应。东卡罗来纳大学硕士论文。 [92] LIDEN , R.C. , WAYNE , S.J., 和 STILWELL,D.(1993)对领导成员交流 19 早期发展的纵向研究。应用心理学杂志, 78(4),662。 work_k5pm52qotfe4nf3iv6kdhozywe ---- A Jeffrey Political geographies of transitional justice cover sheet Newcastle University e-prints Date deposited: 20th June 2011 [made available 1st July 2012] Version of file: Author final Peer Review Status: Peer reviewed Citation for item: Jeffrey A. The Political Geographies of Transitional Justice. Transactions of The Institute of British Geographers 2011, 36(3), 344-359. Further information on publisher website: http://www.blackwell-synergy.com Publisher’s copyright statement: The definitive version is available at www.blackwell-synergy.com DOI link: http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1475-5661.2011.00429.x Always use the definitive version when citing. Use Policy: The full-text may be used and/or reproduced and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not for profit purposes provided that: • A full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • A link is made to the metadata record in Newcastle E-prints • The full text is not changed in any way. The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Robinson Library, University of Newcastle upon Tyne, Newcastle upon Tyne. NE1 7RU. Tel. 0191 222 6000 1 The Political Geographies of Transitional Justice Abstract This paper examines how geographers can contribute to debates concerning transitional justice. Recent scholarship in criminology has identified a residual ‘legalism’ in the enactment and study of transitional justice: trial processes and the perspectives of jurists have been prioritised over wider processes of social healing and the perceptions of non-legal actors. This paper explores how geographers can contribute to challenging this prioritisation of legal processes within the study and practice of transitional justice. This is achieved through an examination of attempts to establish forms of transitional justice in Bosnia and Herzegovina since the end of the war in 1995. Specifically, the paper explores the establishment in 2005 of the War Crimes Chamber of the Court of Bosnia and Herzegovina and the civil society-based strategies it has employed to reach out to witnesses and victim populations. The paper makes two interlinked arguments. First, it examines how the international response to the war in BiH placed justice at a distance from victim communities. Second, the paper argues that civil society activities undertaken to widen access to justice have opened up new spaces of deliberation and critique. It is argued that these spatialities point to possibilities of deliberative conceptions of justice fostered beyond legal institutions and processes. Keywords Bosnia and Herzegovina, Transitional Justice, Political Geography, Law, Civil Society 2 Introduction There has been a wealth of recent work in geography examining the spatial nature and effects of legal mechanisms and discourses. This work has spanned traditional sub- disciplinary areas, and exceeds a neatly-delineated sphere of legal geography (Blomley 2008; Blomley et al. 2001). In this paper I will explore how this work can enrich understandings and practices of transitional justice. While state legal mechanisms and international law have both captured the attention of geographical scholars, rather less work has focused on the spatial aspects of judicial mechanisms set up in periods of political transformation and change. As a corrective, I argue that geographers can contribute to understanding transitional justice by exploring the spaces through which judicial processes operate and the spatial imaginaries they bring into being. This argument challenges prevailing narratives of transitional justice that have foregrounded legal institutions, individuals and knowledge as the focal point of transitional justice, to the exclusion of wider spheres of practice and reflection. While legal practices are rightly key elements of transitional justice responses, these operate through and summon into existence a series of non-legal spaces and actors. This argument is made in response to a growing sense in affiliated disciplines, particularly criminology, that the study of transitional justice has been characterised by a dominance of ‘legalism’ (McEvoy 2007). This term is used to indicate the privileging of legal institutions within attempts to foster transitional justice and the allied dominance of the perspectives of lawyers and judges within scholarly and policy debates. In intellectual terms, legalism can be understood as a process which 3 seeks to separate law from other social sciences; most notably politics (McEvoy 2007; Shklar 1986). I will argue that a legalistic understanding of transitional justice elevates the significance of certain spaces and spatial practices (for example, courts and legal processes) over the wider institutional and political setting in which they operate (including, though not restricted to, human rights NGOs, political parties and state agencies). Consequently this paper seeks to destabilise a legalistic understanding of transitional justice and highlight the spatial practices of non-legal institutions and individuals. In order to illustrate this argument the paper draws on empirical material relating to the establishment of the War Crimes Chamber (WCC) of the Court of Bosnia and Herzegovina (CBiH) and its attempts to build links with victims of, and witnesses to, the war crimes committed during the 1992-5 conflict. Since 2005 the WCC has been granted jurisdiction over intermediate and lower-ranking war crimes cases.1 The Chamber will take a lead role in remaining war crimes cases following the completion of the mandate of the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (ICTY) at the end of the trial of Radovan Karadžić, at a date expected to be in 2012. In an attempt to build links with communities in Bosnia and Herzegovina (BiH) the Court established, in 2006, a Court Support Network (CSN) comprising five NGOs located in towns across the country. This paper assesses the establishment of this outreach initiative and the new spatialities of justice that it has created. The activities of the CSN point to the importance of non-legal agencies to the completion of legal processes. In addition the qualitative responses of the NGO members point to innovative configurations of space, law and justice that operate outside of the formal 4 legal processes. These situated knowledges challenge a narrow legalistic understanding of transitional justice and illustrate the production of new imaginaries of justice and the future. In disciplinary terms this argument contributes to the work of legal geographers in challenging the conception of law operating outside or ‘above’ the society it serves. In ethical and political terms, the empirical material illustrates the importance of non-legal actors and spaces in generating deliberative notions of just outcomes following conflict. The empirical material is drawn from qualitative research conducted during residential fieldwork in the Bosnian towns of Sarajevo, Mostar and Bijeljina in January 2007 and October 2009, building on a long-term research engagement examining the nature of international intervention in BiH since 1999. Taking seriously Megoran’s (2006, 622) call for greater emphasis within political geographic inquiry on “people’s experience and everyday understandings of the phenomena under question”, this approach seeks to explore the mundane and prosaic operation of new legal mechanisms in BiH as they shape, and are shaped by, the civil society organisations under examination. The research visits involved twenty-five semi- structured interviews with representatives from the Court (in particular the Court Public Information and Outreach division), from wider judicial bodies such as the ICTY liaison team in Sarajevo, with other international organisations such as the Office of the High Representative (OHR), United Nations Development Programme (UNDP) and the European Commission and with NGOs both within and beyond the CSN. In addition, the research involved translating and reviewing institutional literature from the Court, the ICTY and the NGO community. 5 The first section of the paper outlines how geographers have explored the relationship between law and space, work that provides critical insights to the production of legal knowledge and its ability to produce spatial outcomes. The second section outlines the history of transitional justice, focusing in particular on its operation through temporal and spatial distance. In the third section I outline a critical geopolitics of justice in BiH, exploring in particular how the international response to the Bosnian war has shaped the possibilities and format of subsequent judicial interventions. The forth section examines the establishment of the Court of Bosnia and Herzegovina, drawing on the wider context of the international response to the war in Bosnia and Herzegovina. The fifth section draws on the empirical material to illustrate the role played by NGOs in supporting the work of the war crimes chamber, focusing in particular on the ‘invited’ and ‘invented’ spaces of justice that have been produced. The Political Geographies of Law The adoption of social and cultural theory into the discipline of geography since the early 1980s has enriched understandings of the relationship between law and space (Blomley 2008). Mirroring theoretical advances in other areas of the discipline, this scholarship has often drawn on Foucault’s explorations of the relationship to between power and knowledge to explore law as a form of discourse (Foucault 1980; Herbert 1996). This approach highlights the grounding of law in particular historical and geographical contexts, and its simultaneous capacity to produce spatial arrangements and erase or exclude others. One of the key objects of concern for this work is the 6 relationship between law and state spatiality. As David Delaney (2001) identifies, the conventional distinction between ‘domestic’ and ‘international’ law renders state sovereignty at the heart of understandings of legal spatiality. In a sense, the centrality of the state points to a wider ‘territorial trap’ (Agnew 1994) in legal studies, whereby state territoriality is presented as a pre-existing spatial framework within and between which legal obligations and rights operate in a systematic fashion. This straightforward understanding of the spatiality of law has been challenged by geographers who have sought to explore the productive capacity of legal discourses to produce spatial arrangements. Consequently scholars have drawn inspiration from this understanding of law as a performance of, and through, space. For example Sallie Marston (2004) examines the spatial effects of legal judgements on the participation of a gay, lesbian and bisexual group in the St. Patrick’s Day parade in Boston, Massachusetts. Marston explores how the legal processes ‘fixed’ certain understandings of society, space and culture. Significantly, these were not neutral definitions of these concepts, but were rather served to promote understandings of society that excluded groups that did not conform to hegemonic expectations. By tracing the path of legislation through the US State and Supreme courts, Marston highlights the way in which legal judgements hinged on a particular understanding of society and space that held them as distinct spheres, rather than as “mutually constitutive processes” (Marston 2004, 11). Marston argues that this separation had profound consequences for how culture was understood as a commodity that belongs to one group rather than “something that is constantly negotiated and transformed through the public give and take of changing 7 ideas and meaning systems in a changing world” (Marston 2004, 14). Within this account legal decisions are not technical adjudications on an external reality, but are rather incursions of power that categorise the social world in order to endorse dominant conceptualisations of identity and belonging. More recently scholars have turned to the materiality of legal practices to confront the perception of law as “a universal abstraction, set apart from the messy realities of local particularities” (Blomley 2008, 161). This work has illuminated the spaces through which legal authority is produced, for example through court rooms, government departments and international bureaucracies (Gregory 2007; Kuus Forthcoming; Latour 2010). By employing ethnographic methodologies to study the materials and contexts of law making, scholars have highlighted the role of everyday bureaucratic processes in shaping legal outcomes, challenging the notion of a clear separation between law and society. In addition to troubling the purity of legal knowledge, these insights highlight the enrolment of spatial abstraction in producing legal authority, from the micro-geographies of the body and the court room, through to the separation of legal buildings from surrounding infrastructures. From this largely geographical work examining the experiential and material attributes of the state-law relationship emerges a concern with the production of legal knowledge and its ability to bring certain subjectivities and spaces into being. One of the key insights shared by these strands of work is the recognition that the operation of law exceeds the arenas conventionally set out for the performance of legal dramas. Just as scholars have sought to question the rigid distinction between state and 8 society, the mutual co-constitution of law and society can therefore be traced through social practices and routines. Drawing on these insights, I would argue that law is a socially embedded process of knowledge production that enrols individuals and institutions beyond the confines of law courts and judicial pronouncements. This approach highlights the governmental nature of legal discourses, where spaces and subjects are labelled and organised through the practice of law. But this framework also focuses attention on the necessity of understanding the ways in which purportedly ‘non-legal’ actors and institutions are drawn into the practice of law. This focus on the substance of law orientates attention to the nature of human agency within legal processes. As the scholarship in legal and political geography has primed us to expect, individuals are not benign recipients of legal discourses but actively constitute and resist these discourses through their everyday lives. In order to conceptualise this notion of agency I will draw on Miraftab and Wills’s (2005) account of activism against water and electricity privatisation in the Western Cape in South Africa. This research stratifies citizenship into ‘invited’ and ‘invented’ practices, illuminating a distinction between formal (‘invited’) notions of neoliberal citizenship centred on voting rights and the consumption of private services, and more improvised (‘invented’) understandings of citizenship focusing on human rights and equality (see also Cornwall, 2002). This vocabulary has spatial implications. In material terms this work illuminates the ‘invented’ spaces through which struggles over citizenship were performed: the street, the home and the infrastructure of the city. In more imaginative terms, this work demonstrates the ways in which ‘invented’ citizenship relied on forms of solidarity that operate across a series of spatial scales 9 within and beyond the state: from the neighbourhood, to the city and through to transnational ties with other activist groups. The use of legal instruments to implement transitional justice in BiH can be analysed through this distinction between ‘invited’ and ‘invented’ practices. This approach illustrates the ways in which formal sites of justice are simultaneously sustained and challenged through invented practices embedded in civil society. It also illustrates the plural spatiality of transitional justice beyond state territoriality. Applying this mode of spatial inquiry to the case of transitional justice requires an exploration of the particular nature of such legal initiatives and their emergence over the past century. The Distance of Transitional Justice The United Nations Security Council define transitional justice as the “full range of processes and mechanism’s associated with a society’s attempts to come to terms with a legacy of past abuses, in order to ensure accountability, serve justice and achieve reconciliation” (United Nations Security Council 2004, 4). While this definition is by no means uncontested (see Teitel 2003), it serves as a starting point for an analysis of the ways in which transitional justice operates through distance. This distance can be articulated in three ways. First, transitional justice operates across a temporal shift, namely that the crimes and the judicial response are occurring at different times, under purportedly different regimes. Consequently, written in to varying definitions of the concept of transitional 10 justice is a sense of the passage of time, setting a distance between crime and punishment. In early attempts to establish instruments of transitional justice this distancing opened legal questions as to the possibility of trying individuals for crimes committed under different legal rule sets. Specifically, the Nuremburg Trials at the end of WWII were criticised at the time for instituting ex post facto law, and challenging the fundamental legal principle of nullum crimen sine lege, nulla poena sine lege (no crime without a law, no punishment without a law) (Kerr and Mobekk 2007, 20). Despite the codification of war crimes in the Geneva Conventions in 1949, the challenge of trying individuals under new legal and political circumstances remains. The significance of shifting political contexts was illustrated in Radovan Karadžić’s pre-trial defence at the ICTY in 2009, where he argued that he had secured immunity from prosecution from the US chief peace negotiator during the Bosnian War, Richard Holbrooke. While refuted by Holbrooke (2008) -- though seemingly confirmed by recent anonymous US State Department accounts (see Klemenčič, 2009) -- this attempt to challenge the jurisdiction of the court illustrates the space opened for contestation through the time delay between crime and trial. In addition to the changing political and legal context, the temporal shift also poses logistical problems for the operation of transitional justice. There are clear challenges to conducting trials after the crimes are alleged to take place, for examples the mortality of witnesses, victims and offender and the degradation of material evidence. Secondly, the institutions of transitional justice are often spatially removed from the context within which the crimes took place. Sriram and Ross (2007, 46) describe this as the ‘externalisation of justice’, where “trials and legal processes occur far from the 11 locus of the crime”. This is most evident in the cases of the tribunals for the conflicts Yugoslavia and the International Criminal Court (ICC) which are both currently based in The Hague in the Netherlands. But even where domestic tribunals or court facilities are used, their sites are often separated from the geographical context of the crimes and victim communities, either through their location in the capital city or through security measures separating the courts from surrounding infrastructures. The Gacaca courts in Rwanda, which have attempted to institute more traditional dispute resolution mechanisms, offer an example of a more socially-embedded legal process (Clark 2007). But even in these attempts, the justice process is confronting a social and demographic context that has radically changed through the conflict and post- conflict periods. In cases such as the former Yugoslavia the displacement and migration of victim communities means that courts often have to face the logistical challenge of gaining testimony from witnesses and victims distributed across the globe. But even where refugees have returned, internal displacements and demographic changes can pose a challenge to the operation of justice. The Rwandan programme of Imidugudu (‘villagisation’) undertaken since 1997 provides an example of the role of government sponsored social engineering creating new spatial challenges to the operation of transitional justice, where former social ties are disrupted and potential trial participants re-distributed across the territory of the state (see van Leeuwen, 2001) 2. Attempts have been made to address the temporal and spatial separation of legal mechanisms of transitional justice from the societies and contexts within which the crimes took place. Notable examples include the establishment of the Truth and 12 Reconciliation Commission (TRC) in South Africa to confront the crimes of the apartheid or the hybrid international/local courts established in Timor-Leste and Cambodia. But these institutional responses do not detract from a third form of distancing: the use of law. While institutional forms of transitional justice have varied over the last century, they have been structured around the use of law as a mechanism through which justice may be sought. This approach has prioritised the establishment of new judicial institutions and the design of new legal and criminal codes through which crimes may be prosecuted. This is necessarily a practice of distancing, where contestation is removed from its social context and evaluated court rooms and legal chambers. The reliance of legal authority on a degree of separation from “local particularities” (Blomley 2008) has engendered a policy response by international organisations, such as the UN, who have adopted programmes in order to widen “access to justice” (UNDP 2010). These large scale policy formulations have cultivated civil society responses who have sought to build connections between court processes and community groups (see Hodžić 2010). In the following sections the paper examines how widening access to transitional justice trials in BiH has not only assisted in the formal legal process, but has brought new spaces of justice into being through education programmes, transnational connections and innovative forms of political participation. These constitute invented rather than invited spaces of law, where civil society organisations bring into existence new deliberative forms of justice. Critical Geopolitics of Justice 13 The distancing of transitional justice has been a particular issue in the case of the international response to the fragmentation of Yugoslavia and, in particular, the war in BiH between 1992-5. The abstraction of judicial instruments from the context of the crimes, both spatially and temporally, has increased the necessity for forms of public outreach to generate understanding of, and cooperation with, the institutions of transitional justice. Exploring this process requires a consideration of the history of international involvement in addressing the violence of the Bosnian war. But in doing so it is important to avoid presenting a neat historical narrative of the international response to the conflict, since these protean historical and geographical events are only intelligible through their complexity and specificity. In order to challenge dominant narratives as essential truths scholars have drawn on post-structural political theory to present a critical geopolitics of the conflict, which illustrates the competing and coexisting discourses that framed the military and political strategies during the conflict and post-conflict periods (see Campbell 1998; O Tuathail 1996; O Tuathail 2002). As Merje Kuus (2007, 10) points out, discourses do not ‘cause’ a particular judicial outcome, but rather “frame political debate in such a way as to make certain policies seem reasonable and feasible while marginalizing other policy options as unreasonable and unfeasible.” By exploring these intertwining discourses we begin to see how the separation of transitional justice mechanisms from Bosnian society was a necessary part of the operation of intervention. 14 The first discursive frame is that of national security. The initial political and military confrontations in BiH in 1992 were framed by nationalist leaders (both within BiH and in other former Yugoslav republics) in terms of competing understandings of national security, structured around mutual fear of minority status in new state territorialities. Political groups representing Bosnian Muslims (or Bosniaks) and Croats feared Serb political dominance in what remained of the Yugoslav state (following the secession of Croatia and Slovenia in 1991). In contrast, Serb nationalist political parties, in particular the Srpska demokratska stranka (SDS) led by Radovan Karadžić, feared minority status in an independent BiH. These fears fuelled antagonistic political rhetoric which transformed into violence following the Bosnian Government’s declaration of independence in April 1992 (see Silber and Little 1996). Over the following months Serb military and paramilitary forces, supported by well- armed Yugoslav People’s Army (JNA), attempted to create an ethnically homogenous territory within BiH, called the Republika Srpska (or RS) (Kadrić 1998). This action involved the expulsion or execution of non-Serb populations, the besieging of key cities such as Sarajevo and Goražde, and the holding of prisoner populations in a series of camps in Prijedor, Brčko and Bijeljina, amongst others (Dahlman and O Tuathail 2005a). Similar atrocities, if on a smaller scale, were committed by groups claiming to represent Bosniak or Croat national interests, in particular in the southern Bosnian towns of Konjic, Mostar and Čelebići. The second discursive frame was humanitarianism. Western political elites portrayed the violence as a humanitarian disaster (O Tuathail 2002), focusing attention on the plight of Bosnian citizenry in particular in the besieged streets of Sarajevo. This 15 biopolitical label drew attention to the outcome of violence and the failure of the state to perform its function of protecting its citizenry, but it simultaneously erased a conception of victim and perpetrator. Presenting the conflict in these terms allowed for an institutional response that focuses on the distribution of aid and promotion of NGOs. The humanitarian label was sustained through explanations by politicians in the US and UK that the violence was a consequence of ‘ancient ethnic hatreds’ or ‘primordial evil’, labels that present conflict as biologically-predetermined and an essential part of a Balkan temperament rather than as a political manoeuvre. The outcome of this primordial understanding of the violence was an attempt to identify a division of Bosnian territory which would appease all warring parties (Campbell 1998). In doing so, we can see how the rubric of humanitarianism only sustained the discursive framing of the conflict in terms of national security. Alongside the entwined discourses of national security and humanitarianism there circulated a third discursive frame of the Bosnian war: accountability. The images of war crimes broadcast through international media networks, in particular the pictures of emaciated Bosniak men behind barbed wire at the Omarska prison camp in 1992, jarred with discourses of national security or humanitarianism. The organic narrative of violence encapsulated by a humanitarian interpretation of the conflict was challenged by the outpouring of public and political fury provoked by reports of war crimes and displaced people. As Ó Tuathail (1996) notes, allegations of genocide in Europe raised the spectre of the impotence of Western Allies in the face of the Holocaust in World War Two and the subsequent commitment to ‘never again’ stand by while atrocities on such scale were committed. As a response to these apparent 16 violations of the Geneva Conventions in October 1992 the UN Security Council established a commission of experts to investigate alleged war crimes in BiH. The findings of this commission led to pressure within the UN to establish a Tribunal to hold individuals to account for the acts against civilians in BiH. The material outcome of these pressures was the establishment by the United Nations Security Council of the International Criminal Tribunal for the Former Yugoslavia (ICTY) through Resolution 827 on May 25 1993. The Resolution tasked the tribunal with “prosecuting persons responsible for serious violations of international humanitarian law committed in the territory of the former Yugoslavia” from January 1991 onwards (United Nations Security Council 1993). As Hazan (2004) has illustrated, this institutional response was shaped by the dominant discourse of the conflict of national security. The initial work of the Tribunal was hampered by poor resourcing and internal disputes between the panel of international judges and the first chief prosecutor, Richard Goldstone. A particular criticism levelled by the jurists was the extremely slow pace of initial indictments and the focus placed by Goldstone on lower-level military officers rather than targeting wartime leaders. In this respect, Hazan (2004, 61) suggests that Goldstone was performing a political function for Western leaders by intimidating the leadership of warring parties, but “stopping short of indicting them.” In addition, local and national courts and prosecution offices across the territory of the former Yugoslavia began (and continued) conducting war crimes cases lists of alleged perpetrators. As Mallinder (2009) notes, minority groups perceived these practices as reflecting the political interests of the demographic majority in a particular locality. In February 17 1996 the Bosnian Government formally agreed to halt the arrest of individuals who has been indicted by the ICTY, in a set of procedures know as the Rules of the Road. The discourse of national security was further emboldened through the internationally-brokered resolution to the violence in BiH. As the work of Campbell (1998) has demonstrated, the Dayton Peace Accords (DPA) in 1995 emphasised a commitment to ethnically-defined territories, albeit with the paradoxical guarantee of the right of return for refugees and internally displaced people. While this outcome reproduces a discourse of national security, it could be argued that concerns over accountability acted as a backdrop to Dayton negotiations, in particular since Radovan Karadžić and Bosnian Serb Army General Ratko Mladić were indicted for a second time during the negotiation process (see Goldstone 2000, 107-8) and compliance with the ICTY was written in to Annex 6 (Chapter 3) of the resulting Peace Accords. But despite these moves, in the immediate post-conflict period the momentum for the judicial response to the violence was lost, reflected in the shift to language of democratisation, in particular prioritising democratic elections that strengthened nationalist political parties (see Donais 2000) and the weak terms of engagement for the NATO implementation force (I-For) which acted as a barrier to the arrest of indicted individuals.3 This outcome ensured that the judicial instruments designed to hold war criminals to account were located at a distance to the localities at which the crimes took place. The devolved nature of the Bosnian state, and the subsequent strength of the entity-level governments, resulted in political stagnation in creating a single legal entity capable 18 of performing war crimes trials in BiH (Jeffrey, 2009). The powers of the international community have been concentrated in the Office of the High Representative (OHR), and singularly in the figure of the High Representative, an appointee of the Peace Implementation Council (PIC). Since 1997 the High Representative has held Bonn Powers, named after the PIC conference at which they were authorised, which grant executive and legislative powers over the Bosnian state in the name of implementing the Dayton Agreement. In the face of “centrifugal forces”, the OHR has used Bonn Powers to make basics reforms to elements of the education system, the divided military and stagnating system of government (International Crisis Group 2007). A critical study of the geopolitical framing of the war in BiH can therefore draw a connection between the international endorsement of discourses of national security, and the resultant fragmented state dependent upon international supervision with strong executive and legislative powers. The War Crimes Chamber One of the key impositions made by then High Representative Lord Paddy Ashdown on 3 July 2002 was to impose The Law on the Court of Bosnia and Herzegovina, legislation that established for the first time the possibility of a state level court in BiH. This was realised in March 2005 through a joint initiative between the ICTY and OHR established the War Crimes Chamber of the Court of Bosnia and Herzegovina. This organisation, operating within the Criminal Division of the Court of Bosnia and Herzegovina, accepted transferred cases from the ICTY in addition to commencing new prosecutions and investigations. 19 There are a number of important facets to the WCC. First, from the outset this body has been supported by international personnel within both the Prosecutor’s Office and Judiciary. This involvement is unpopular with domestic political parties, in particular within the RS, and in October 2009 the Bosnian Government ordered for international participation to cease, though was over-ruled by the High Representative. Second, the trials take place within the Court of Bosnia and Herzegovina building, located five kilometres south of the centre of Sarajevo (see Figure 1). The building, funded by the European Union and Government of Japan, contains eight court rooms each constructed and equipped through funding from multilateral and bilateral sources. Figure 2 shows Courtroom 6, a high security facility funded by the Belgian Government and used in high profile war crimes cases. [Figure 1 and Figure 2 about here] Through analysis of the discursive framing of the violence in BiH we can discern three reasons for the necessity of a public outreach initiative involving NGOs in fostering understanding in the work of the WCC. First, the WCC is a new institutional response to the violence of the conflict and consequently it may be unfamiliar to communities in BiH. Certainly the PIOS official suggested that there is a longer legacy of perceiving courts as removed from wider society in the former Yugoslavia: The idea was that people felt more comfortable contacting an NGO than contacting a court, people were concerned about contacting courts, they were not seen as accessible, this was a 20 legacy of the Yugoslav past where courts were always seen as up here [gestures with her hands]. So people didn’t want to contact the court.4 Second, the origins of the WCC in OHR decision-making and the subsequent involvement of an international judiciary has led to the Court being seen as international imposition by some segments of the Bosnian public. This is often not meant as a criticism; indeed many of the NGO officials I interviewed for this research saw the retention of an international judiciary as crucial to the continued functioning of the court. However, the international presence was identified by both the Bosnian Court official and the ICTY Liaison Officer as a key reason to promote public outreach in order to build community trust in the judicial process. Finally, the establishment of the WCC was strongly opposed by nationalist politicians in BiH, in particular Milorad Dodik’s Savez nezavisnih socijaldemokrata (SNSD) party in the RS. This domestic hostility to the WCC, coupled with the novelty of this institutional form and the perception of international imposition, strengthened attempts within the court to establish some form of public outreach initiative5. This came to fruition in 2005 with the creation of PIOS as part of the CBiH, and specifically with attempts to create links with Bosnian NGOs working in the fields of human rights, education and reconciliation. Invited and Invented Spaces of Justice The Court Support Network (CSN) was established by PIOS in 2005. Its mission was “to integrate the mission of the Court into the wider Bosnian community,”6 an 21 objective that one of the instigators described as “more than PR.”7 The Court approached five human rights NGOs located in the Bosnian towns of Sarajevo (Žene ženama), Mostar (Centri civilnih inicijativa or CCI), Prijedor (Izvor), Bijeljina (Helsinški komitet) and Tuzla (Forum građana). The idea was to reach a wide geographical spread and through these organisations establish a sustainable network which would spread information about the Court, and in particular the WCC.8 The original CSN programme was funded by the Court for six months and provided resources to each NGO to dedicate two staff to work on networking activities. One of the key objectives behind the CSN was for the organisations involved to develop their own network, and thus the reach of the court would extend into Bosnian communities through the operation of civil society groups. After the end of the first phase of funding this had not been achieved and one of the officials involved remarked that the lack of follow-up funding was a reflection of changing priorities in PIOS away from outreach work and towards public and media relations.9 But despite the weakening of the formal network approach, the participant NGOs have continued to work with the Court (and in particular the WCC) and have remained in loose affiliation while the concept of the CSN remains a core part of the Court’s public relations materials . As part of this research project I examined the activities in detail of two of the organisations within the CSN: CCI in southern town of Mostar and Helsinški komitet in the northern town of Bijeljina. Through the interviews with these organisations, and studying their promotional and policy documentation, ambiguities emerge as to the position and nature of their activities. While providing logistical assistance to the trial process, these organisations also offer space for critique and rejection of the 22 mechanisms of transitional justice initiated in BiH since the end of the war. In order to illustrate these diverse functions I am drawing on the framework introduced by Miraftab and Wills (2005) to group them under the headings ‘invited’ and ‘invented’ spaces of justice. As discussed earlier in the paper, these labels provide a sense of the agency of the CSN institutions as they operated both within and beyond the roles prescribed by PIOS and the WCC. Consistent with the main argument of the paper, these functions illustrate the significance of non-legal institutions and practices in shaping the legal process and offering alternative spaces of transitional justice. I will explore each in turn. Invited Spaces “The Court Support Network was meant to be for all the [Bosnian] public” related an official from the CCI, “but it was mostly used by potential witnesses.”10 This comment encapsulates what was perceived by both those managing and participating in the CSN: that its primary focus was on encouraging and supporting witnesses of war crimes to come forward and testify at the WCC. Part of this function was logistical, providing the Court and, in particular, the prosecutor’s office with assistance in getting in touch with witnesses, assisting with transportation arrangements and keeping contacts open between witnesses and court officials. But this narrow interpretation of the role of the CSN overlooks the ways in which these apparently mundane practices are reshaped by the political and economic geographies of post-Dayton BiH. In particular two challenges confronted the CSN organisations: the prioritisation of social and economic considerations over participation in the court 23 and the stigmatisation of participation by sections of the community that resist the establishment of a state court and/or institutions of transitional justice. In the first case the representative from CCI was explicit that participation in trial processes was a low priority for those struggling to survive in the tough economic conditions of contemporary BiH where GDP per capita in 2009 was only $7764 (UNDP 2009a): So our idea was that if you have some basic problems, like of you cannot feed your children how can you decide to go to the court of BiH and be a witness, I mean this is not a priority in your life.11 In order to confront this issue the organisation sought to provide a broad approach to witness support that understood the importance of economic, social and psychological factors in shaping decision making processes. One activity undertaken by CCI was informing witnesses of their potential eligibility to receive a small state pension on behalf of deceased relatives who were recognised as Civil Victim of War.12 The representative explained the struggle in convincing people that they were eligible for this money: When we told them you have a right to this money, they would say “no, who is going to give us money?” You know, people didn’t trust anything. Even if you explain to them the law and their rights, they are sceptical about many things.13 24 These quotations illustrate the disjuncture between the existence of certain legal or judicial rights, and their adoption by potential witnesses. The simple invitation to participate – whether in the WCC process or through the civil victim status – was insufficient to ensure involvement. By exploring the individual motivations for individual participation and coupling this with psychological barriers to trust in authority structures the CSN was able to foster participation. The CSN were adept at presenting the activities of the WCC as embedded in the social context of BiH post- Dayton . This point was further enforced through the interview comments regarding the wider Bosnian political landscape and its effect on participation rates. The interviewees spoke of the significant role played by the dominance of nationalist political parties in shaping participation in the WCC. In particular they pointed to the role of mythical tales of heroic war time leaders in shaping public opinion. To one extent this reflects the sustained primacy of discourses of national security in shaping domestic politics in BiH over the last fifteen years. But the interviews suggested that this was also reflective of the distanced nature of transitional justice over this period. The absence of an ICTY-led public outreach initiative until 1999 was blamed by a representative from Helsinški komitet for providing the space for the political manipulation of transitional justice in BiH: […] it was a basic mistake they [the ICTY] made in the beginning. The ICTY was established in 1993 but the outreach office of the ICTY was established in 1999. These six years were 25 used by political leaders in the regionto use cases in front of the ICTY for their political agendas.14 The perceived failure of the ICTY to reach out to potential witnesses in the past therefore reverberated into the present through the unfavourable political contexts for participation in the WCC. The CSN NGOs sought to break down this animosity by introducing schemes that foster trust in the WCC, and these initiatives involved a range of economic, psychological and political strategies. For example, CCI teamed up with a mental health NGO to provide psychological support for potential witnesses that faced the dual challenge of revisiting past traumas while risking being labelled a traitor by segments of their community on account of their participation with the WCC. In sum, the trial assistance offered by the CSN was crucial to the operation of war crimes trials at the WCC in Sarajevo. By embedding the trial process in the economic and social context in contemporary BiH, the NGOs were able to foster participation in the legal process. Contrary to abstracting law from society, this work involved the careful grounding of these processes in the communities and localities within which the crimes took place and in which victims and witnesses continue to seek redress. Invented Spaces In addition to the work supporting the trial process, the CSN organisations have been performing a broader role outside the operation of the WCC since 2005. Through a range of workshops, seminars and cultural events, the NGOs were seeking to foster 26 public debate concerning the nature of transitional justice in BiH. These actions were ‘invented’ as they demonstrated the ability of these organisations to operate outside the legal process and summon into existence new spaces of deliberation over the nature of transitional justice in BiH. These practices illustrated a more nuanced spatiality of justice in Bosnia. Perhaps most explicitly they bring into view the range of physical spaces that are drawn upon as part of the judicial process. Coffee shops, homes, university campuses and individual human bodies are brought into the practice of transitional justice through these improvised activities. But they also illustrate the enrolment of a range of imaginative geographies that are enrolled into the practice of transitional justice, such as universal human rights, cosmopolitan senses of belonging and nostalgia for Yugoslav solidarity. While these activities often supported the approach of the WCC they also included opportunities for critique and the hope for alternative judicial arrangements in the future. By their disparate and, at times, improvised nature these activities defy easy categorisation, but in order to illustrate aspects of their effects I will examine two processes: community workshops and university education. First, the NGOs sought to localise the legal process by organising workshops involving victim groups, legal representatives and NGO staff within the communities in which the crimes took place. Such events involved prosecutors talking through the evidence as it was presented and jurists explaining the sentence (if passed) and fielding questions concerning the trial process. The interactive component of the event posed logistical problems for the NGOs, since there was often high demand amongst victim groups to attend and there was resistance from NGO staff to turn people away. 27 The success of this format has seen it adopted by the ICTY which has recently organised similar workshops in BiH to explain case decisions. Of course, such events are not simply a transfer from legal experts to local communities. The NGO representatives discussed how new prosecutions had occurred after victim groups had approached prosecutors, emboldened by hearing about successful prosecutions in other cases. While the trial workshops required considerable involvement of the WCC and prosecutor’s office, the NGOs stressed the forms of local knowledge and contacts required to organise such events. Through family connections, personal experiences and professional relationships the NGOs had developed networks with war crime victims that were vital in securing their participation in the workshops. These connections allowed the NGOs to bring together antagonistic victim groups into single-site workshops: But the biggest issue is actually the preparation work. It is a much bigger issue to get in the same place people from different ethnic communities who are perceived as victims. For example you have to spend three days drinking rakija [plum brandy] with [name] if you want him to come. Or in some villages you have to convince [name] to come to the Čelebići case. It just needs time. And in some cases they have the experience other from other NGOs who come and say ‘we need three victims to talk about something’, but that is not how it works, they are not on standby.15 This comment encapsulates the forms of knowledge brought into the process of transitional justice by the CSN NGOs. It also demonstrates the ways in which the 28 space of transitional justice extended beyond the hired workshop venue, and brings into view the rakija stall, the kafana (coffee shop) and the homes of victims. But this account illustrates more than the micro-geographies through which public outreach operates; it also reflects a different conception of the figure of the individual within judicial programmes. The reference to ‘not being on standby’ illustrates the ways in which participation was conceived by the Helsinški komitet as a human process of negotiation that required established bonds and trust rather than a mechanistic process of participation in a formal legal process. The NGOs stressed that the localisation of judicial processes was more than a ‘communicative’ strategy; it sought to shift the focus of transitional justice from perpetrators onto victims. The retributive judicial approach employed by both the ICTY and the WCC has, they argued, orientated attention on those who committed crimes as opposed to those who had been victims. This situation has been exacerbated by the close allegiance between media outlets and nationalist political parties, a relationship that the NGOs felt had promoted the heroism of wartime leaders and served to question the veracity of reports of mass atrocities during the war. One case that was repeatedly cited during the research process was that of Radovan Stanković. Stanković was a fighter in the Bosnian Serb Army who was sentenced in March 2007 to 20 years’ imprisonment for the crimes of systematic rape and imprisonment of women in what was termed Karamanova kuća (Karaman’s house) in Foća municipality during 1992. But in May 2007 Stanković escaped from prison, since he was sent to serve his sentence in Foća, a place where he had previously claimed that it would be easy to escape on the basis of his friends and contacts (see Balkan 29 Investigative Reporting Network 2007). This case illustrates the weaknesses in the Bosnian prison system; where despite plans there is no state-level prison (penal governance is devolved to the RS and the Federation). But more significantly, subsequently Stanković has refuted the charges through communication with RS newspapers. The effect of these processes was explained by the representative from Helsinški komitet: In the RS there was no public space given to the presentation of facts. There is enough space given for Stanković to send letters from wherever he lives now, explaining that this is an attack on the Serb people and he is not guilty, and they gave him two pages in the newspapers. But no one is giving space to those who suffered. To the girl who is now 26 years old, or 27, and she is more dead than alive because she was kept for three months in Karaman’s House and was systematically raped by more than 20 soldiers. The Stanković case provides an acute example of the coupling of judicial failure and the capture of news media by the interests of hard-line nationalist political parties. The response of the NGOs has been to provide spaces such as the workshops through which victims may meet and challenge the formal judicial structures through debate and questions. Part of this process relates to a desire to reshape the ‘invited’ spaces of justice through changes in the penal strategy, providing greater clarity in sentencing decisions and improving specific aspects of access to the judicial process. But more significantly, these activities also illustrate the way in which the CSN envisages a different form of justice that shifts attention away from retribution and orientates attention on restorative notions of deliberation and reconciliation. One of the key points made by each of the NGOs is that the workshops must be attended by 30 representatives from each of the parties in the conflict, and mix civilians with veterans. As the representative from CCI emphasised, “we have all been victims in some part of our lives.” This was in part a reference to her own personal experience, but also drew attention to a key point: that the CSN was attempting to reconceptualise justice as a shared experience rather than a legal process. The second set of activities that brought into existence invented spaces of justice related to education. All the CSN NGOs have strong education components within their portfolio of activities. For Helsinški komitet this involved university-level education in transitional justice, exercised through a series of different channels. First, the organisation has sought to introduce the specifics of the WCC into law degrees across the RS: We made an announcement through law students in the RS, so I did several groups throughout the year bringing them to the court, to talk to the president of the court, the main prosecutor, to see a trial and how it is organised and to see the court, witness preparation and protection and to talk to other NGOs who are working with victims. And we had more than 3000 students pass this.16 As stated earlier in the discussion, there is considerable political animosity towards the WCC in the RS so these activities mark a considerable achievement in sharing information concerning the legal processes in BiH. But in order to build on this success the organisation had developed a second approach to university-level education: designing a module on transitional justice and human rights to be run in the University of Bijeljina. During the interview the NGO official said with a smile that 31 they had described the module as concerning “intercultural understanding and non- violent communication”17 since this was unlikely to raise objections from university administrators, in a way that mentioning the WCC or transitional justice might. This initiative began with 83 students in October 2009 but there are hopes to expand: We are starting with the Bijeljina Faculty, then Mostar is going to start Eastern Sarajevo, Pale they are going to start next year and then Sarajevo is going to start next year. […] On the other side we are currently working on making a group of professors from law schools from five different universities, political science departments, the journalism departments, and social sciences and we are going to work with them for one year to make it possible to see how much of transitional justice they can actually put in a formal education frame, what they would need, on what they could agree, and how to teach it. This focus on university education illustrates the significant emphasis placed on setting the terms of public debate concerning transitional justice. One of the repeated concerns of NGOs members both within and beyond the CSN was the media presentation of transitional justice as ‘simply’ the actions of the ICTY and WCC, rather than discussing the nature and implications of different approaches to justice after war. In the absence of a unified commemoration of the conflict and the associated fragmented historical narratives of the past, these approaches placed the WCC in a historical and theoretical context. This approach sought to shift attention away from the particulars of the BiH context and think through more cosmopolitan understandings of justice and rights. This ‘invented’ space moves beyond the physical realm of the campus and seminar room, to confront the imaginative geographies enrolled in processes of transitional justice. 32 Drawing the distinction between invited and invented spaces of justice illuminates the role played by the CSN in the operation of transitional justice in BiH. While these accounts provide a vivid illustration of the importance of civil society actors in facilitating the trial process, they also demonstrate how these organisations conceive of justice in radically different ways to those offered through the formal legal institutions. This does not mean law is marginalised, the NGOs considered its operation vital to generating a sense of accountability amongst victim population. Instead, the legal process was presented as a starting point which provoked public debate and the potential to bring victim groups together to discuss common concerns. Through the legal process the CSN was able to create a series of spaces of justice as a more deliberative practice. Conclusions Towards the end of the fieldwork process I had arranged a meeting with the Programme Manager of UNDP BiH’s Access to Justice programme at their head office in Sarajevo. This initiative provides assistance to the CBiH through training of the judiciary, capacity-building Bosnian state agencies and providing material support for the court (such as office furniture and IT equipment). After we had introduced ourselves I explained the purpose of my research and my interest in the WCC’s outreach projects. “Ah,” replied the Programme Manager, “you are interested in questions of ‘soft’ justice, we are currently interested in questions of ‘hard’ justice.”18 The Programme Manger’s use of this distinction was a surprise considering the 33 UNDP’s commitment to fostering civil society engagement with processes of transitional justice in BiH (see UNDP, 2009b). But in doing so the UNDP official was deploying well-established categories demarcating legal from non-legal approaches. But these labels do not simply describe judicial practice but structure regimes of thought on transitional justice. The distinction of ‘hard’ and ‘soft’ justice supports the conception that there is a possibility of separating these two arenas, where the ‘hard’ legal processes operate in isolation from the ‘soft’ social, political and spatial settings within which they are embedded. This separation is reflected in the wider scholarly study of transitional justice that has explored the nature of legal processes at the expense of either wider non-legal activities or the constructed nature of the legal/non- legal binary. This paper has offered a corrective by examining the contribution of a geographical analysis on the study of transitional justice in BiH. There are two specific outcomes from this argument. Firstly, the study of the critical geopolitics of the conflict and post-conflict periods illuminates the spacing of transitional justice in BiH. The presentation of the violence by war-time leaders as a necessity to ensure national security, and the validation of these imaginaries at the Dayton Peace Accords, ensured that legal processes of justice remained remote from the locations where the crimes took place. This distance was reflected through the physical location of the ICTY at The Hague and the executive control over the process by international supervisory agencies in Bosnia (most notably the OHR). But perhaps most profoundly, this distance is reflected in the prominence given to legal processes as the primary implement of justice. This form of judicial response has set the tone for the nature of 34 post-conflict justice in BiH, specifically focusing on a retributive programme that seeks to hold war criminals to account, rather than a restorative process that seeks to establish shared truths and build trust between antagonistic groups. As a second geographical lens this paper has examined how the political and scholarly focus on legal processes has marginalised a series of non-legal spaces, actors and practices. Through the examination of the prosaic operation of the CSN a more complex spatiality of transitional justice emerged. Using the analytical distinction developed by Miraftab and Wills (2005), these were explored through the framework of ‘invited’ and ‘invented’ spaces of justice. This brought to the fore the centrality of CSN organisations in facilitating the work of the WCC by supporting witness testimony and establishing contact with victims. But the work of the CSN extended beyond these instrumental practices, since they were using their contacts with victim groups to establish practices of justice that were operated beyond the formal legal process. These activities work through a series of geographies: such as the coffee shop, the seminar room, the campus and the human body. But inventing such improvised spaces of deliberation over justice required conveying normative arguments for the kinds of transnational solidarity and rights that were at the heart of transitional justice programmes. In this sense invented spaces of justice sought to look beyond the BiH state territory and foster conceptions of common humanity and transnational belonging. In contrast to the retributive mode of formal judicial practices, the improvised activities were often structured around deliberation and confrontation. This more agonistic approach provided space for victims to offer 35 critiques of the formal trial processes and sought to embed legal mechanisms in the context of wider scholarly and policy reflection on the nature of justice. Notes 1 A central component of the completion strategy of the ICTY comprises the transfer of cases against “intermediate and lower-level accused to competent national jurisdictions” in BiH, Croatia and Serbia (ICTY, 2010). While sensitive cases will remain under the jurisdiction of the WCC, other war crimes cases in BiH are expected to be devolved to courts in the Republika Srpska and the Muslim-Croat Federation. 2 I am grateful to an anonymous referee for bring this literature and issue to my attention. 3 The first arrest by the NATO-led multinational force in Bosnia (then S-For) was Milan Kovacević on 10 July 1997. 4 PIOS Official, Sarajevo October 8th 2009. 5 ICTY Liaison Officer and co-instigator of the CSN, Sarajevo October 9th 2009. 6 ICTY Liaison Officer and co-instigator of the CSN, Sarajevo October 9th 2009. 7 ICTY Liaison Officer and co-instigator of the CSN, Sarajevo October 9th 2009. 8 PIOS Official, Sarajevo October 8th 2009. 9 ICTY Liaison Officer and co-instigator of the CSN, Sarajevo October 9th 2009. 10 Member of Centre for Civil Initiative Official, Mostar October 12th 2009. 11 Member of Centre for Civil Initiative Official, Mostar October 12th 2009. 12 The legislation differs in the RS and Federation, but both offer pensions for victims of war that suffer ‘60% or more’ physical disability including death or disappearance (see FBiH Law on Principles of Social Protection, Protection of Civil Victims of War and Protection of Families with Children, article 54 Official Gazette of the FBiH no. 36/99 and The Law on Protection of Civil Victims of War , article 2 Official Gazette of RS, no. 25/93) 13 Member of Centre for Civil Initiative Official, Mostar October 12th 2009 14 Member of Helsinški komitet, Bijeljina October 18th 2009. 15 Member of Helsinški komitet, Bijeljina October 18th 2009, the names of two prominent victims have been removed to protect anonymity. 16 Member of Helsinški komitet, Bijeljina October 18th 2009. 17 Member of Helsinški komitet, Bijeljina October 18th 2009. 18 Programme Manager of UNDP Access to Justice BiH, Sarajevo October 15th 2009. 36 References Agnew J 1994 The Territorial Trap: The Geographical Assumptions of International Relation Theory. Review of International Political Economy 1: 53-80 Balkan Investigative Reporting Network 2007 Stanković Still at Large (http://www.bim.ba/en/65/10/3139/) Accessed March 10 2010 Blomley N 2008 Making Space for Law. in Cox K, Low M and Robinson J eds The Sage Handbook of Political Geography Sage, London Blomley N, Delaney D and Ford R T 2001 Preface: Where is Law? in Blomley N, Delaney D and Ford R T eds The Legal Geographies Reader: Law, Power, and Space. Blackwell Publishers, Oxford Campbell D 1998 National Deconstruction: Violence, Identity and Justice in Bosnia. University of Minnesota Press, Minnesota Clark P 2007 Hybridity, Holism and ‘Traditional’ Justice: The Case of the Gacaca Community Courts in Post-Genocide Rwanda. George Washington International Law Review 39: 765-838 Cornwall A 2002 Locating Citizen participation. IDS Bulletin 33: i-x Dahlman C and O Tuathail G 2005a Broken Bosnia: The Localized Geopolitics of Displacement and Return in Two Bosnian Places. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 95: 644-62 Delaney D 2001 Introduction: Globalization and Law. in Blomley N, Delaney D and Ford R T eds The Legal Geographies Reader: Law, Power and Space. Blackwell, Oxford 252-5 37 Donais T 2000 Division and Democracy: Bosnia's Post-Dayton Elections. in Spencer M ed The Lessons of Yugoslavia. JAI Elsevier Science, London 229-58 Foucault M 1980 Power/Knowledge. Pantheon, New York Goldstone R 2000 For Humanirty Reflections of a War Crimes Investigator. Yale University Press, New Haven Gregory D 2007 Vanishing Points. in Gregory D and Pred A eds Violent Geographies Fear, Terror and Political Violence. Routledge, New York Hazan P 2004 Justice in a time of war: the true story behind the international criminal tribunal for the former Yugoslavia. Texas A & M University Press, College Station Herbert S 1996 The geopolitics of the police: Foucault, disciplinary power and the tactics of the Los Angeles Police Department. Political Geography 15: 47-59 Hodžić R 2010 Living the Legacy of Mass Atrocities: Victims' Perspectives on War Crimes Trials. J Int Criminal Justice 8: 113-36 Holbrooke R 2008 The face of evil. The Guardian, London International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia 2010 Mandate and Jurisdiction (http://www.icty.org/sid/320) Accessed March 5 2010 International Crisis Group 2005 Bosnia's Stalled Police Reform: No Progress, No EU. International Crisis Group, Sarajevo/Brussels International Crisis Group 2007 Ensuring Bosnia’s Future: A New International Engagement Strategy. International Crisis Group, Sarajevo/Brussels Jeffrey A 2009 Justice incomplete: Radovan Karađžić, the ICTY and the spaces of international law. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 27: 387- 402. 38 Kadric J 1998 Brcko: Genocide and Testimony. Institute for the Research of Crimes Against Humanity and International Law, Sarajevo Kerr R and Mobekk E 2007 Peace and Justice Seeking Accountability After War. Polity Press, Cambridge Kuus M 2007 Geopolitics Reframed: Security and Identity in Europe's Eastern Enlargement. Palgrave Macmillan, New York and Houndmills Kuus M Forthcoming Geopolitics, Bureaucracy and Place: The Case of the European Quarter. Global Networks: Journal of Transnational Affairs Latour B 2010 The Making of Law. Polity Press, Cambridge Marston S 2004 Space, culture, state: uneven developments in political geography. Political Geography 23: 1-16 Mallinder L 2009 Retribution, Restitution and Reconciliation: Limited Amnesty in Bosnia-Herzegovina Queen’s University Belfast, unpublished thesis McEvoy K 2007 Beyond legalism: Towards a thicker understanding of transitional justice. Journal of Law and Society 34: 411-40 Megoran N 2006 For ethnography in political geography: Experiencing and re- imagining Ferghana Valley boundary closures Political Geography 25: 622-40 Miraftab F and Wills S 2005 Insurgency and Spaces of Active Citizenship. Journal of Planning Education and Research 25: 200-17 O Tuathail G 1996 Critical Geopolitics. Routledge, London O Tuathail G 2002 Theorizing practical geopolitical reasoning: the case of the United States' response to the war in Bosnia. Political Geography 21: 601-28 Shklar J N 1986 Legalism: law, morals, and political trials. Harvard University Press, London 39 Silber L and Little A 1996 The Death of Yugoslavia. Penguin Books Ltd, London Sriram C and Ross A 2007 Geographies of Crime and Justice: Contemporary Transitional Justice and the Creation of 'Zones of Impunity'. The International Journal of Transitional Justice 1: 25-65 Teitel R 2003 Transitional Justice Genealogy. Harvard Human Rights Journal 69: 69-94 UNDP 2009a Human Development Report Bosnia and Herzegovina. United Nations Development Programme, Sarajevo UNDP 2009b Transitional Justices Guidebook for Bosnia and Herzegovina. United nations Development programme, Sarajevo UNDP 2010 Bosnia and Herzegovina: Supporting National Capacities in Transitional Justice for Bosnia and Herzegovina (http://europeandcis.undp.org/governance/hrj/show/158DB1B0-F203-1EE9- BEC1296F057C98A6) Accessed March 5 2010 United Nations Security Council 1993 Resolution 827 (http://www.un.org/Docs/scres/1993/scres93.htm) Accessed February 18 2010 United Nations Security Council 2004 The Rule of Law and Transitional Justice in Conflict and Post-Conflict Societies. United Nations, New York 1-24 work_k6sxhrqzeff5pbvm5q26lwyqx4 ---- Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike 3.0 Unported License. | 01 law .. - Jan 01 1970 02:00:00 AM cks_2011_law_art_001.pdf 480KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:19 PM cks_2011_law_art_002.pdf 458KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:19 PM cks_2011_law_art_003.pdf 409KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:20 PM cks_2011_law_art_004.pdf 572KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:20 PM cks_2011_law_art_005.pdf 411KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:20 PM cks_2011_law_art_006.pdf 424KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:20 PM cks_2011_law_art_007.pdf 350KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:20 PM cks_2011_law_art_008.pdf 214KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:20 PM cks_2011_law_art_009.pdf 286KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:20 PM cks_2011_law_art_010.pdf 490KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:20 PM cks_2011_law_art_011.pdf 310KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:20 PM cks_2011_law_art_012.pdf 319KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:20 PM cks_2011_law_art_013.pdf 230KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:20 PM cks_2011_law_art_014.pdf 407KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:20 PM cks_2011_law_art_015.pdf 250KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:20 PM cks_2011_law_art_016.pdf 309KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:20 PM cks_2011_law_art_017.pdf 418KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:20 PM cks_2011_law_art_018.pdf 544KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:20 PM cks_2011_law_art_019.pdf 302KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:20 PM cks_2011_law_art_020.pdf 222KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:20 PM cks_2011_law_art_021.pdf 420KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:20 PM cks_2011_law_art_022.pdf 311KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:20 PM cks_2011_law_art_023.pdf 587KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:20 PM cks_2011_law_art_024.pdf 697KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:20 PM cks_2011_law_art_025.pdf 349KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:21 PM cks_2011_law_art_026.pdf 554KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:21 PM cks_2011_law_art_027.pdf 307KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:21 PM cks_2011_law_art_028.pdf 503KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:21 PM cks_2011_law_art_029.pdf 299KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:21 PM cks_2011_law_art_030.pdf 311KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:21 PM cks_2011_law_art_031.pdf 271KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:21 PM cks_2011_law_art_032.pdf 253KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:21 PM cks_2011_law_art_033.pdf 546KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:21 PM cks_2011_law_art_034.pdf 554KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:21 PM cks_2011_law_art_035.pdf 589KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:21 PM cks_2011_law_art_036.pdf 367KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:21 PM cks_2011_law_art_037.pdf 441KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:21 PM cks_2011_law_art_038.pdf 489KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:21 PM cks_2011_law_art_039.pdf 537KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:21 PM cks_2011_law_art_040.pdf 530KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:21 PM cks_2011_law_art_041.pdf 291KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:21 PM cks_2011_law_art_042.pdf 297KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:21 PM cks_2011_law_art_043.pdf 264KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:21 PM cks_2011_law_art_044.pdf 422KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:21 PM cks_2011_law_art_045.pdf 392KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:21 PM cks_2011_law_art_046.pdf 314KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:21 PM cks_2011_law_art_047.pdf 290KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:21 PM cks_2011_law_art_048.pdf 404KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:21 PM cks_2011_law_art_049.pdf 452KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:21 PM cks_2011_law_art_050.pdf 364KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:22 PM cks_2011_law_art_051.pdf 335KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:22 PM cks_2011_law_art_052.pdf 383KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:22 PM cks_2011_law_art_053.pdf 505KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:22 PM cks_2011_law_art_054.pdf 310KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:22 PM cks_2011_law_art_055.pdf 292KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:22 PM cks_2011_law_art_056.pdf 469KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:22 PM cks_2011_law_art_057.pdf 581KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:22 PM cks_2011_law_art_058.pdf 350KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:22 PM cks_2011_law_art_059.pdf 349KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:22 PM cks_2011_law_art_060.pdf 333KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:22 PM cks_2011_law_art_061.pdf 373KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:22 PM cks_2011_law_art_062.pdf 370KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:22 PM cks_2011_law_art_063.pdf 320KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:22 PM cks_2011_law_art_064.pdf 325KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:22 PM cks_2011_law_art_065.pdf 357KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:22 PM cks_2011_law_art_066.pdf 327KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:22 PM cks_2011_law_art_067.pdf 297KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:22 PM cks_2011_law_art_068.pdf 404KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:22 PM cks_2011_law_art_069.pdf 432KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:22 PM cks_2011_law_art_070.pdf 370KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:22 PM cks_2011_law_art_071.pdf 429KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:22 PM cks_2011_law_art_072.pdf 364KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:22 PM cks_2011_law_art_073.pdf 444KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:22 PM cks_2011_law_art_074.pdf 504KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:22 PM cks_2011_law_art_075.pdf 289KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:22 PM cks_2011_law_art_076.pdf 393KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:23 PM cks_2011_law_art_077.pdf 347KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:23 PM cks_2011_law_art_078.pdf 560KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:23 PM cks_2011_law_art_079.pdf 396KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:23 PM cks_2011_law_art_080.pdf 351KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:23 PM cks_2011_law_art_081.pdf 348KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:23 PM cks_2011_law_art_082.pdf 285KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:23 PM cks_2011_law_art_083.pdf 344KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:23 PM cks_2011_law_art_084.pdf 681KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:23 PM cks_2011_law_art_085.pdf 589KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:23 PM cks_2011_law_art_086.pdf 598KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:23 PM cks_2011_law_art_087.pdf 354KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:23 PM cks_2011_law_art_088.pdf 392KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:23 PM cks_2011_law_art_089.pdf 357KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:23 PM cks_2011_law_art_090.pdf 669KB Jan 31 2013 01:45:23 PM work_kd5tzgihbnbtpn363d4ipyuram ---- 25458.indd Book review 1398 The Journal of Clinical Investigation http://www.jci.org Volume 115 Number 6 June 2005 DNA and the criminal justice system The technology of justice David Lazer, editor Massachusetts Institute of Technology Press. Cambridge, Massachusetts, USA. 2004. 424 pp. $67.00. ISBN 0-262-12265-0 (hardcover). 424 pp. $27.00. ISBN 0-262-62186-X (paperback). Reviewed by Max M. Houck West Virginia University, Morgantown, West Virginia, USA. E-mail: max.houck@mail.wvu.edu As is its biological wont, DNA has an evolving role in the justice system. No lon- ger a tool only for the prosecution, DNA testing has become a part of post-convic- tion review, a sometimes-appropriate model for what is considered science by the courts, and may eventually be of assistance to the investigator in the field. DNA’s biologic centrality makes these actual and potential forensic applications at once powerful and concerning. The legal and scientific com- munities debate the utility of forensic DNA analysis from 2 very different professional mindsets. Attorneys de facto are biased because they have clients — they are for or against some proposition brought before the court. They assist their clients through an adversarial process of rhetoric, question- ing, and citing legal precedent. Attorneys have a goal: win. Scientists have a different professional perspective: they are neither for nor against either side — despite the fact that 1 of those sides called them to court — and have no stake in the matter other than representing their science and their work objectively, fairly, and accurately. Scientists communicate through open debate and progress through the incremental accumu- lation of information about the world. In other words, their goal is to understand the world more completely. As a result, attor- neys and scientists tend to view DNA and its forensic uses differently. DNA and the criminal justice system (the title is drawn from a conference of the same name held at the John F. Kennedy School of Gov- ernment in 2000), edited by David Lazer, cap- tures this difference as it explores how DNA is used in the criminal justice system and how it may be used in the future. Read completely, Lazer’s book provides a comprehensive view of the legal issues surrounding forensic DNA testing. The book covers 3 main areas: how DNA testing has affected the criminal justice system; privacy and security concerns; and the creeping use of DNA to predict criminal behavior. Lazer has done a superb job of bal- ancing the chapters and has produced a vol- ume of high quality that will stand as a neces- sary reference for many years to come. The crux of the argument about how DNA has affected the criminal justice system cen- ters on post-conviction DNA testing. With- out a doubt, post-conviction DNA testing has exonerated many innocent individu- als. But does exoneration mean innocence? Just because the defendant’s DNA wasn’t found on crucial evidence doesn’t mean he or she wasn’t involved in the commission of the crime; a sexual assault can still occur without a male ejaculating. “Absence of evi- dence is not evidence of absence,” as the old forensic chestnut goes. The context of the evidence is a primary factor in the interpre- tation of any DNA results. Another lingering question relates to the professional mindset previously discussed — how can DNA results be infallible for exoneration but flawed for conviction? The other side of this coin is reflected in the stubbornness of some prose- cutors who reject post-conviction DNA test- ing because guilty means guilty. These are, notably, biased perspectives and are pitched from the professional stances of those who espouse them. Attorneys that consider DNA testing to be the “gold standard” of science are ignoring what any scientist could tell you: DNA analysis is just another method with benefits and limitations, depending on how you apply it. The debate that courses through the middle portion of the book stems from the potential for abuse of DNA databases. The concern is that medical, genetic, or otherwise personal information will be gleaned from DNA data- bases that reside in the hands of the govern- ment. The DNA profiles used for forensic sci- ence are generated from noncoding sections of the human genome — that is, the sections were specifically chosen because they contain no useful medical or behavioral information. A close understanding of the implications of this fact quells or negates most of the wor- ries expressed in these chapters. What hap- pens to the samples, however, is a more trou- bling situation. Should the DNA samples be retained for potential reanalysis or post-con- viction testing? Yes. Does this place the DNA of those convicted (or those accused, in some cases) in the hands of government? Yes. Are certain demographic groups (i.e., the poor and the non-white) overrepresented in those databases? Sometimes. Interestingly, Sir Alec Jeffries, the scientist who developed the method used in forensic DNA testing, sug- gests that samples from all citizens should be in the forensic database, as that would ensure true equality. The final section of the book discusses the concerns over eugenics and the predic- tion of criminality from a person’s genes. Garland Allen’s chapter on this is excellent and, in my opinion, he settles the argument by concluding, “the kind of data that exist at present simply do not allow us to draw any valid conclusions about a genetic influ- ence in criminal behavior.” The roster of authors is astounding, and each chapter succeeds on its own. Several of the chapters are particularly noteworthy. Fred Bieber’s chapter on the science and technology of forensic DNA profiling is as succinct and well written as any summary of this complicated topic I have read. Mar- garet Berger’s chapter on lessons learned is a well-reasoned argument for post-conviction testing (although her claim that some tra- ditional forensic techniques are “worthless” seems a bit overblown). And finally, Lazer and Michelle Meyer’s consensus and debate sum- mary reifies and condenses the arguments in a thoughtful and concise conclusion. DNA and the criminal justice system is a valuable and insightful reference on law and policy regard- ing the use of DNA in the courts. work_ke6aw3gywvbynkxo5of3juehqi ---- Postmodernizm – co to i po co? Teksty Drugie 1993, 1, s. 74-86 Postmodernizm – co to i po co? Zdzisław Łapiński http://rcin.org.pl Zdzisław Łapiński Postmodernizm — co to i po co? O zróżnicowaniu i tempie przemian literatury dwu- dziestowiecznej — szkoły, kierunki, orientacje! — pisano wiele. Dawniej nieco częściej, teraz nieco rzadziej. Dlaczego nie zaskakuje ciągłość tej literatury? Oświecenie, romantyzm, a cóż dopiero pozytywizm, panowały u nas o wiele krócej. Wystarczy położyć obok siebie dobry wiersz z lat trzydziestych, np. Przybosia z Równania serca (1938), i dobry wiersz współczesny, np. Barańczaka z Widokówki z tego świata (1988), aby odnieść wrażenie, że mimo odrębności poetyk, postaw i emocji są to utwory z tej samej epoki i można je opisywać za pomocą tych samych kategorii. Zdumiewające. W ciągu stulecia przewaliły się przez świat dwie wojny powszechne, zagłada groziła całym narodom, wieloma społeczeństwami wstrząsnęły do samych podstaw totalitarne reżimy, a literacka estetyka trwa w głównych zarysach bez zmian. Nie tylko „Przyboś został, tak jak był, Przybosiem". Pozostała sobą także sztuka XX w., na przekór kazaniom o j e j końcu, po Oświęcimiu. Co więcej, literatura tego stulecia oddaje „ducha epoki" nie gorzej niż robiła to literatura dawniejsza, i to nie zawsze wtedy, gdy heroicznie przeciwstawia się złu lub gdy cynicznie mu się wysługuje. Zachowując ciągłość, literatura ta zmienia jednak nieco swe zabarwienie, przesuwają się w niej akcenty, wyodrębniają dwie fazy. W a r t o te fazy http://rcin.org.pl 75 P O S T M O D E R N I Z M — CO T O I PO CO? nazwać, nawet kosztem przetasowania ustalonej terminologii. Choćby po to, aby łatwiej porozumiewać się z historykami innych niż nasza literatur. Jak wiadomo, nowe nazwy są już w użyciu: modernizm i postmodernizm. Ten pierwszy występuje w głównych językach europejskich w dwojakim sensie. W szerszym — obejmuje całą cywilizację nowożytną (ang. modernity). W węższym — nowoczesną wysoką kulturę (ang. moder- nism). Nowożytność jest rozumiana dosyć tradycyjnie — od Renesansu, choć chętnie podkreśla się znaczenie XVII w., ze względu na kartezjanizm i jego następstwa w filozofii i naukach przyrodniczych. Natomiast nowoczesność to te zjawiska kultury, które wystąpiły w ostatnich dekadach XIX w. i trwały mniej więcej do połowy XX w. Na dwa sposoby bywa także rozumiany postmodernizm. Albo jako przełom podobny do tego, który oddzielił nas od średniowiecza, a więc cezura byłaby bardzo głęboka i dotyczyła wszystkich dziedzin życia, albo też j a k o przezwyciężenie pewnych tylko dążeń, głównie intelek- tualnych i artystycznych, panujących w dobie nowoczesności. (Dobrze służą temu w angielszczyźnie dwie odrębne formy rzeczownikowe: postmodernity i postmodernism, natomiast zamieszanie wprowadza przymiotnik postmodern, nie różnicujący owych znaczeń.1) Przekonanie, że nowoczesność już się wyczerpała i że powstaje coś nowego, co trzeba nazwać, i że prowizorycznie można się posłużyć słowem postmodernism — pojawiło się w Stanach na początku lat sześćdziesiątych. Następnie słowo to zawędrowało do Francji i Niemiec, tam krzyżowało się często z pojęciem „po-nowożytności", a następnie wróciło do Ameryki, wzbogacone o nowe, szersze konotacje filozoficzne i społeczne. Modernizm (nowoczesność) w tym ujęciu to przede wszystkim dążenia wywodzące się z symbolizmu. Kierunki radykalniejsze — futuryzm, ekspresjonizm, dada, surrealizm — schodzą wówczas na dalszy plan. Takie spojrzenie wynika pewnie z faktu, że klasycy nowoczesności — Proust, Rilke, Kafka, Valéry, Joyce, Mann, Eliot, Bieły, Mandelsztam, Achmatowa — związani są z tym nurtem zachowawczym. Gdybyśmy jednak skupili uwagę na różnych awangardzistach tego okresu, to 1 Z tych możliwości zawartych w angielszczyźnie jej użytkownicy korzystają jednak niechętnie: wielki słownik oksfordzki (OED), w wydaniu z 1989 r., wprawdzie uwzględnia hasło post-modern i odnotowuje formy post-modernism i post-modernist, ale nie zauważa post-modernity. http://rcin.org.pl ZDZISŁAW ŁAPIŃSKI 76 postmodernizm okazałby się nie tyle zaprzeczeniem modernizmu, co próbą wskrzeszenia jego wyczerpanej już w Europie witalności2. Kontrast między Europą a Stanami Zjednoczonymi jest zresztą dla wielu krytyków kluczowy. Np. według Andreasa Huyssena awangarda pierwszych dziesięcioleci naszego wieku dlatego nie mogła przyjąć się w Stanach, że tradycyjna wysoka kultura nie zapuściła tam jeszcze korzeni dość głęboko. Henry James, Ezra Pound i T. S. Eliot stawiali sobie za cel europeizację sztuki amerykańskiej, czyli import wyszukanych form artystycznych. Dopiero w latach sześćdziesiątych powstają w Ameryce warunki dla kontrkultury i dla odnowionej awangardy, która pod nazwą postmodernizmu zacznie z kolei wpływać na myśl i sztukę europejską.3 Istnieje chyba jednak jakaś alchemia, która sprawia, że podobne struk- tury artystyczne mogą występować w niepodobnych warunkach socjo- -politycznych. Zaprojektowane w określonej sytuacji, powtarzane by- wają w sytuacji zupełnie innej, a mimo to doskonale spełniają tam nowe funkcje. I wszystkie one, oglądane z dystansu, stają się składnikiem wspólnej, nadrzędnej sytuacji mentalnej. Aby nie poddawać się bez reszty deterministycznemu poglądowi, łączą- cemu w sposób jednoznaczny postmodernizm w sztuce z określonymi warunkami panującymi w społeczeństwach rozwiniętych, warto może przypomnieć, że wielkie nazwiska tej formacji literackiej — Jorge Luis Borges (ur. 1899), Samuel Beckett (ur. 1906) oraz Witold Gombrowicz (ur. 1904), którego nie wahałbym się postawić na czele — to ludzie 2 Zupełnie inaczej interpretuje te związki Włodzimierz Bolecki (Polowanie na postmoder- nistów). Postmodernizm dla niego to negatywna reakcja na kierunki awangardowe. Myślę, że zaciążył tu punkt widzenia teoretyków architektury. Dla nich awangarda to nie żadne dadaizmy i surrealizmy, ale konstruktywizm, Bauhaus, funkcjonalizm, Styl Między- narodowy, słowem — racjonalizacja sztuki. Architekci, którzy już na początku dyskusji o postmodernizmie mieli w niej swój udział i spopularyzowali bardziej niż inni samą nazwę, wprowadzili jednocześnie sporo zamętu. Nie sądzę, aby właśnie architektura, sztuka nieprzedstawiająca, mogła nam służyć za paradygmat. Problematyka postmoder- nizmu dla historyka i teoretyka literatury, jak zresztą i dla filozofa, obraca się wokół pojęć takich jak „referencja", „reprezentacja" czy „podmiotowość", nie znajdujących dobrego odpowiednika w architekturze. Aby uniknąć nieporozumień, dodam, że estetykę Przybosia łączę z modernizmem. U nas istotnie dążenia postmodernistyczne skrystalizowały się m. in. w atakach na „awangar- dyzm" tego autora. 3 Por. A. Huyssen After the Great Divide: Modernism, Mass Culture and Postmodernism, London 1988. http://rcin.org.pl 77 P O S T M O D E R N I Z M — CO TO I PO CO? mniej więcej tego samego pokolenia, ukształtowani w latach, kiedy nikt 0 postmodernizmie nie słyszał, i pochodzący z krajów o zacofanej gospodarce, patriarchalnej obyczajowości i katolickich tradycjach (Ar- gentyna, Irlandia, Polska). Wszyscy trzej zetknęli się natomiast dosyć wcześnie ze środowiskiem paryskiej bohemy w latach międzywojennych.4 To, co jest centrum (tak!) postmodernizmu, tzn. jego sztuka i filozofia, w swych najcenniejszych przejawach powstało mocą wewnętrznej logiki, z prób przezwyciężenia kanonu modernistycznego, z jednej strony, 1 idealistycznej filozofii niemieckiej, z drugiej. Próby te pobudzane były nową wrażliwością, ale wrażliwość tę wykazywali tylko nieliczni. Do- piero pod wpływem nie dających się wcześniej przewidzieć procesów globalnych wypracowane przez małe grupki pięknoduchów techniki odczuwania i wyrażania odczuć, myślenia i nadawania myślom kształtu, zostały powszechnie zaakceptowane. Punktem zwrotnym stało się przeszczepienie pewnej estetyki i praktyki artystycznej z literatury i innych sztuk na nowe dziedziny. Postmoder- nizm jako zjawisko kompleksowe, obejmujące nie tylko sztukę, ale i całą humanistykę, także nauki społeczne, a nawet styl bycia, i pod- porządkowane (dosyć enigmatycznej) ideologii — zapanował dopiero dzięki francuskim myślicielom poststrukturalnym, głównie dekonstruk- cjonistom. Najwdzięczniejszym terenem ekspansji w ciągu ostatnich dwudziestu lat okazała się Ameryka. Przyczółkami stały się uczelnie, a psychospołecznych przesłanek dostarczyła studencka rewolta z końca lat sześćdziesiątych. W debatach politycznych prowadzonych w kręgach radykalnych przez obrońców i przeciwników postmodernizmu daje się często słyszeć pewna fałszywa nuta. A to dlatego, że obie strony starają się zataić fakt (na szczęście, dobrze im znany!), że jedynie społeczeństwo postprzemysłowe, 0 ustroju demokracji parlamentarnej, ze wszystkimi swymi najważniej- szymi instytucjami, takimi, jakie są, a nie takimi, jakie można sobie wymarzyć, potrafi zapewnić warunki życia umysłowego i życia w ogóle, do których intelektualiści przywykli i bez których nie mogliby się obyć. Osławiona wywrotowość postmodernizmu podlega zwykle samokontroli 1 — wbrew nadziejom jednych, a obawom drugich — nie stanowi zagrożenia dla systemu. 4 Tylko niewielka poprawka wniesiona do współrzędnych pozwoliłaby wprowadzić czwarte, i ostatnie, wielkie nazwisko — Władimira N a b o k o v a (ur. 1899). http://rcin.org.pl ZDZISŁAW ŁAPIŃSKI 78 Tak więc w debatach tych jest nie tylko wiele zamieszania pojęciowego, ale i „świadomości fałszywej". A jak się rzecz gmatwa, gdy spróbujemy zastosować kategorię postmodernizmu do społeczeństw komunistycz- nych i postkomunistycznych! Na pierwszy rzut oka żadnych tu zbieżności. Warunki — polityczne, ekonomiczne, społeczne — były pod każdym względem tak różne, że jakiekolwiek próby objęcia zjawisk umysłowych tą samą siatką pojęcio- wą z góry powinny być skazane na niepowodzenie. A jednak. Myślę, że bez naciągania rzeczywistości do gotowych formułek i schematów można zestawić pewne zdarzenia u nas i na Zachodzie dzięki nie tylko powierzchownym podobieństwom formalnym, ale i podobieństwom funkcjonalnym. Poczynając bowiem od drugiej połowy lat pięćdziesiątych wytworzyła się u nas sytuacja sprzyjająca temu, co nazywane teraz bywa „aurą postmodernistyczną". Życie umysłowe toczyło się wtedy w wyraźnie określonych ramach politycznych. Panowała opinia, że choć można zmodyfikować ustrój, to nie można go obalić (przynajmniej w bliskiej przyszłości). Nie można, ale i nie trzeba. Ton bowiem nadawał marksistowski rewizjonizm. Krytycyzm wobec wielu aspektów marksizmu jako teorii i chęć wyko- rzenienia praktyk stalinowskich szły w parze z nieufnością do gospodarki kapitalistycznej. Mimo wszystkie śmiesznostki — i tragedie — tamtych lat, przemiana była potężna. Znowu byliśmy w literackiej Europie. Chłonęliśmy nawet to, co tam dopiero pączkowało. Stąd też dobre przyjęcie, jakie spotkało później — już w fazie świadomego siebie postmodernizmu — naszych twórców na Zachodzie. Mistrzem nad mistrzami tego okresu stał się Gombrowicz. Filozofem najbardziej wpływowym wśród młodych intelektualistów — Kołakow- ski. Najbardziej podziwianym eksperymentatorem w poezji — Biało- szewski. Równocześnie zaczynał się kult młodopolskiego z ducha prekur- sora postmodernizmu — Witkacego. W recepcji dramatu europejskiego najtrwalej zapisała się sztuka Becketta Czekając na Godota, wystawiona przez Jerzego Kreczmara we Współczesnym. Wtedy też uformował się teatr Kantora i Grotowskiego. A j a k o fenomen sztuki masowej objawił się „Kabaret Starszych Panów". Witkacy jest typowym pisarzem okresu przejściowego. Tęsknotę do metafizyki łączy z poczuciem jej niemożliwości w świecie współczesnym. Bezceremonialność, z jaką podchodzi on do sztuki, jej zasad i granic. http://rcin.org.pl 79 P O S T M O D E R N I Z M — CO TO I PO CO? podszyta jest żądzą sztuki absolutnej. Nienawiść do kultury masowej przeplata się z fascynacją. Zasada tragifarsy rządzi każdym rodzajem ekspresji Witkacego, nie wyłączając spraw osobistych. Pastisz i parodia to techniki stosowane przez niego bez opamiętania. Podobnie auto- referencjalność oraz mieszanie fikcji i faktów. Wreszcie to, co przez długi czas nie pozwalało zaakceptować Witkacego tak, jak na to zasłużył — „bylejakość" jego sztuki, jakieś niespełnienie czy niedopełnienie — to antywartość, która dla postmodernistów staje się właśnie jakością poszukiwaną. Jako ucieleśnienie postmodernizmu, w jego wczesnym, a przecie doj- rzałym kształcie, można traktować Gombrowicza. Nie będę śledził poszczególnych stron tej twórczości, to się samo narzuca. Dotknę tylko dwu spraw ogólniejszych. Otóż antysztuka, do jakiej dąży postmoder- nizm, wyłania z siebie wiele nieprzezwyciężonych aporii. Witkacy był tyleż odkrywcą owych aporii, co ich ofiarą. Gombrowicz natomiast umiał nad nimi zapanować i uczynić z nich skuteczny środek wyrazu. Jego bunt przeciw arcydziełom i poszukiwanie sztuki zbrukanej, nie dbającej o swoją nieskazitelność, przyniósł nową formę, a z nią nową doskonałość, mniej ostentacyjną, za to organizującą sfery nie tknięte dotąd przez literaturę. Niedbałość znajduje się pod ścisłym nadzorem estetycznym. Podobnie stosunek do czytelnika. Autor na pozór powierza mu beztrosko siebie i swoje kolejne utwory, naprawdę zaś stara się, w sposób niemal obsesyjny, zaaranżować każdy jego odruch. Dezyn- woltura artystyczna Gombrowicza to tylko zręczny chwyt iluzjonisty, mający ukryć jego jedyną wiarę, wiarę w sztukę, i jego całkowite oddanie tej sztuce. Przełom lat pięćdziesiątych i sześćdziesiątych sprzyjał nastrojom postmo- dernistycznym. Panowało przekonanie, że najgroźniejszy jest dogma- tyzm, absolutyzowanie zasad i reguł, podczas gdy żadnych z nich absolu- tyzować nie wolno. „Dogmatyzm" w żargonie partyjnym był eufemisty- cznym określeniem zastępującym słowo „stalinizm". Ale antydogmatyzm w sensie potocznym dobrze oddaje ówczesne nastroje (por. np. Etykę bez kodeksu Kołakowskiego). Nie darmo też obok „dogmatyzmu" wykorzys- tywano inne pojęcia związane z instytucją religii, takie jak „inkwizycja". Komunizm, swoista parodia teologii, obrzędu i organizacji kościelnej, był atakowany za pomocą bezpiecznych wówczas metafor z zakresu religii, rozrastających się często w alegoryczne fabuły (Andrzejewskiego Ciemności kryją ziemię, Kołakowskiego Klucz niebieski, Brezy Spiżowa http://rcin.org.pl ZDZISŁAW ŁAPIŃSKI 80 brama). Ale i samo myślenie metafizyczne nie budziło respektu. Przewa- żał klimat agnostycyzmu. Istniało też przekonanie, że skoro perspektyw na zasadniczą zmianę nie ma i trzeba się urządzić w obrębie zreformowanego świata dotych- czasowego, to najlepszą bronią w walce o większą swobodę jest ironia, szyderstwo, paradoks, poczucie relatywizmu, świadomość, że historią rządzi przypadek lub naga siła. Ten zespół idei, postaw i praktyk pisarskich tworzył pewną wyczuwalną całość. Nie ma co owijać w bawełnę — to gomułkowszczyzna zrodziła polski postmodernizm. Kres temu położył Marzec 68. Losy wymienio- nych autorów potoczyły się rozmaicie. Większość z nich kontynuowała swój projekt. Znaleźli też epigonów i następców. Ustalił się wówczas kanon — głównie dzięki Sandauerowi — który można dzisiaj nazwać kanonem modernistycznych i postmodernistycznych mistrzów: Leśmian, Schulz, Przyboś, Gombrowicz, Białoszewski. Zaczynają jednak brać górę inne zainteresowania. Wymowna była popularność poetyki wypracowanej przez autorów Nowej Fali, wyko- rzystujących składniki postmodernistyczne swoich poprzedników („poe- zja lingwistyczna"), ale instrumentalnie — w celu stworzenia sztuki perswazyjnej, z tezą, otwarcie zbuntowanej. W inny sposób, lecz także po to, aby zjadliwie komentować aktualia, posługiwał się postmoder- nistycznymi technikami prozatorskimi Konwicki. Bardziej dwuznaczny pod względem politycznym był Tadeusz Różewicz, z premedytacją odwołujący się w swoim „teatrze absurdu" do kontekstu europejskiej neoawangardy. Najbardziej prawomyślną odmianę postmodernizmu uprawiali prozaicy spod znaku „Twórczości". Był to nurt podwójnie konformistyczny — wobec naśladowanych wzorów zachodnich i wobec oficjalnego życia instytucjonalnego. Aby to nadrobić, autorzy ci uciekali się zwykle do ekstrawagancji formalnych i skandalizującej tematyki obyczajowej. Nie mogło to się spotkać z życzliwością czytelników i do pewnego stopnia kompromitowało problematykę postmodernistów w oczach krytyki. Może jestem stronniczy, ale sądzę, że rumieńców nabrała ta problema- tyka na łamach „Tekstów". Był to już okres poststrukturalizmu we Francji i „Teksty", nawiązując do niego wprost, choć nie bezkrytycznie, zaczęły rewidować panujące założenia metodologiczne oraz interpreto- wać na nowo — zgodnie z rozbudzoną wrażliwością polityczną — obraz naszej literatury powojennej. Z brawurą wykonywał to Janusz Sławiń- http://rcin.org.pl 81 P O S T M O D E R N I Z M — CO TO I PO CO? ski, podważając solidną konstrukcję polskiego strukturalizmu, wznie- sioną nieco wcześniej przy jego walnym udziale i dalej zresztą wspieraną przez niego w pracach o charakterze akademickim (co dowodzi, jak dobrze pojął on lekcję dekonstrukcjonistów). Ale mentalność postmodernistyczna — przeniknięta sceptycyzmem, komplikująca nasz stosunek do świata, przejęta własnym rzemiosłem, mimo swych kpin ze sztuki zakotwiczona w światopoglądzie do głębi estetycznym — nie mogła sprostać atmosferze czasów, w których dokonywała się rewolucja. Wichura lat osiemdziesiątych rozwiała resztki „aury postmodernistycznej". Paryskie doktryny i amerykańska praktyka krytyczna spotykały się u humanistów ze wzgardą. Najsubtelniejsi historycy literatury jako przedmiot wiwisekcji wyżej cenili „Trybunę Ludu" niż Leśmiana. Wielu literatów przyjęło śluby ubóstwa artystycz- nego. Następcy Nowej Fali zaczęli uprawiać publicystykę poetycką. Wielkim uznaniem cieszyli się realiści: Marek Nowakowski, Kazimierz Orłoś. Znamienna jest kariera pośmiertna Józefa Mackiewicza, pisarza, którego twórczość znajduje się na przeciwległym krańcu nie tylko post-, ale i modernizmu. Miejsce Gombrowicza jako żywego klasyka zajął Miłosz, wsławiony swymi atakami na „nowoczesność". Wprawdzie on sam dobrze przyswoił i przetrawił współczesne procesy rozkładowe, ale odczytywany był wówczas od strony budującego przesłania. Prawdziwie bałwochwalczą reakcję wywoływały utwory Herberta, poety, który pod osłoną ironii nadawał patetyczny krój postawom, decyzjom i konfliktom tych lat. Dzisiaj jest to rozdział zamknięty. Ale sytuacja bieżąca i perspektywy na przyszłość są dosyć mgliste. Swego czasu u Gombrowicza doszły do głosu wszystkie ważniejsze impulsy postmodernistyczne, a także prze- konanie, że ten styl myślenia nie tylko prowadzi do wewnętrznych sprzeczności (bo to było programowe i nie powinno stanowić zarzutu), ale może ponadto wywołać groźne następstwa praktyczne. Udramaty- zowany obraz tego mamy w Ślubie, w Dzienniku zaś znajdujemy uwagi o umiarze, prostocie i zdrowym rozsądku, jednak dopiero po wyczer- paniu wszystkich skrajności. Wskazówki Gombrowicza (za którymi sam autor nie poszedł) zrealizo- wał po latach Białoszewski, nie w swoich wierszach, lecz w późnej prozie. Proza ta to tylko nieśmiały zarys estetyki — j e d n e j z możliwych estetyk, jakie po przewartościowaniu doświadczeń postmodernistycz- nych mogłyby się przyjąć. Ale czy późne dzieło Białoszewskiego stanowi http://rcin.org.pl ZDZISŁAW ŁAPIŃSKI 82 naprawdę zapowiedź owej estetyki przyszłości? Wątpliwe.5 A bez tej nowej estetyki, sprawdzonej w utworach, o wiele trudniej będzie także pisać w nowy sposób o literaturze. Impas, jaki nastał w badaniach literackich, jest dotkliwy. Najsilniejszego bodźca teorii dostarczała zwykle sama sztuka. Ostatecznie postmodernizm narodził się z na- tchnień, jakie dały wielkie dzieła wcześniejszej epoki. Na pozór wszystko idzie jak najlepiej. Badania literackie zagranicą bogatsze są niż kiedykolwiek w pomysły, szkoły, kierunki. Najbardziej wpływowy jest dekonstrukcjonizm — i to on jest czymś w rodzaju samoświadomości epoki, ale jeszcze lepiej oddaje ową sytuację post- modernistyczna wielość orientacji. Stosunki między tymi orientacjami — dekonstrukcjonizmem, hermeneutyką, neomarksizmem, feminizmem, psychoanalizą itd. — są ambiwalentne. Toczy się zażarta polemika, padają najostrzejsze zarzuty, a równocześnie przenikają się idee i metody. Wzmożonemu zainteresowaniu metodologią (czego dowodem inflacja dysertacji „meta-") bynajmniej nie towarzyszy postulat puryzmu, ani też troska o czystość zasad. Przeciwnie, w cenie jest umiejętność kom- binowania ze sobą ujęć, traktowanych dotąd jako rozdzielne. Cyrkulacja idei, teorii, hipotez i technik badawczych między konkuru- jącymi ze sobą orientacjami rozciąga się na dyscypliny leżące poza literaturoznawstwem. Dawniej był to na ogół ruch jednokierunkowy, od innych dyscyplin ku wiedzy o literaturze. Teraz mamy do czynienia z ruchem dwustronnym. Najbardziej może uderzające są zmiany w nastawieniu filozofów. I to nie „humanistów", ale tych, co jeszcze niedawno wrzucali do jednego worka metafizykę, poezję i czystą ekspresję uczuć, jako rzeczy w tym samym stopniu nie zasługujące na ich uwagę. Mowa tu o neopozytywis- tach, takich jak Nelson Goodman, i ich wychowankach, takich jak Richard Rorty. Dzisiaj dla G o o d m a n a wszelkie poznanie jest arbitralną kreacją, nauka nie różni się w tym od sztuki, a swój dawny rynsztunek logika (jednego z najgłośniejszych w filozofii po wojnie) porzuca on dla metafory, paradoksu, gry słów. Rorty zaś ze swej strony dodaje, iż funkcją filozofii jest nieustająca debata, a raczej rozmowa, dla której najlepszych wzorów dostarcza literatura. Jeśli zaś chodzi o samoświa- 5 Ale por. szkice w pracy zbiorowej Pisanie Bialoszewskiego, Warszawa 1993. Sugerują one, że estetyka Bialoszewskiego jest jednak sygnałem nadchodzących zmian we wraż- liwości literackiej. http://rcin.org.pl 83 P O S T M O D E R N I Z M — CO TO I PO CO? domość metodologiczną, to filozofowie powinni uczyć się u krytyków literackich. W swojej pochwale wiedzy o literaturze Rorty posuwa się zresztą jeszcze dalej. Twierdzi, że w kulturze bogatych społeczeństw demokratycznych, a więc w kulturze postmodernistycznej, wiedza ta zaczyna stopniowo przejmować rolę, jaką dawniej odgrywały — religia, nauka, filozofia.6 A więc z jednej strony jesteśmy świadkami czegoś, co można nazwać rozdrobnieniem i dezorientacją badań literackich, ale z drugiej — ich ekspansji. Jako członkowie światowej mafii zajmującej się zawodowo literaturą możemy wyrażać umiarkowane zadowolenie. Interesują się nami, naśladują nas, rywalizują z nami — i to według naszych włas- nych reguł! Zabawność położenia wynika z tego, że przedstawiciele nauk społecznych chcą naśladować humanistów, a ci — artystów; artyści zaś robią wszystko, aby usunąć sobie grunt spod nóg, kwes- tionując samo pojęcie sztuki. Tak więc kryzys tożsamości daje się wszystkim we znaki. Ożywienie intelektualne jest wyraźne, ale kierunek dążeń niejasny. Myślę jednak, że wiele odrębnych tendencji da się wywieść z tendencji nadrzędnej. Ideę prawdy wypiera idea wolności twórczej, a w związku z tym następuje estetyzacja wielu dziedzin traktowanych dotąd pod kątem poznawczym, etycznym, ideologicznym. Z tej perspektywy cała retoryka wywrotowa i rewolucyjna rysuje się jako gest teatralny. Dla ludzi uwięzionych w klasycznych systemach totalitarnych doj- mującym doznaniem było rozchwianie obiektywnej rzeczywistości, nie dający się pokonać rozdźwięk między bezpośrednim doświadczeniem a powtarzaną przez wszystkich oficjalną wykładnią. Ta schizofrenia społeczna, z taką intuicją i wiedzą oddana przez Orwella, groziła osobistemu zdrowiu psychicznemu. Wiara w obiektywną prawdę dla każdego myślącego człowieka stanowiła artykuł pierwszej potrzeby. U nas zbiorowa pamięć wydarzeń sprzed lat czterdziestu jest jeszcze dość silna, by relatywizm poznawczy mógł nie wywołać niepokoju. Ze wszystkich cech postmodernistycznych ów relatywizm jest chyba naj- bardziej drażniący. Dlatego właśnie chciałbym udzielić głosu jego obrończyni, Barbarze Herrnstein Smith. Zdaniem tej autorki, traktuje 6 Por. N. G o o d m a n Ways of Worldmaking, Indianapolis 1978. i Of Mind and Other Matters, Cambridge, Mass. 1984, oraz R. Rorty Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity, Cambridge (England) 1989. http://rcin.org.pl ZDZISŁAW ŁAPIŃSKI 84 się go zwykle jak postawiony na głowie obiektywizm. Bo obiektywista nie dopuszcza do siebie myśli, że można poważnie brać pod uwagę inną perspektywę, zakładającą całkiem odrębną konceptualizację świata, a więc i inny sens kluczowych słów, inny tryb rozumowania, inną postawę — nie dające się określić przez odwrócenie jego własnych poglądów. Jak sugestywnie pisze ta apologetka nie-obiektywnej filozofii, większość zarzutów formułowana jest w języku, który podlega właśnie zakwestionowaniu. Polemika prowadzona za pomocą tradycyjnych oskarżeń — oskarżeń o wewnętrzną sprzeczność, o brak kryteriów pozwalających odróżnić prawdę od fałszu, dobro od zła i piękno od brzydoty oraz o nieuniknione ponoć skutki społeczne tych poglądów — otóż tego rodzaju polemika, według Herrnstein Smith, może przeko- nać tylko tych, którzy już wcześniej zaakceptowali obiektywistyczne rozumienie takich słów jak „prawda", „rzeczywistość", „wartość", „znaczenie", „referencja" itd. Herrnstein Smith pisze: „Relatywizm" — w sensie koncepcji świata j a k o zjawiska, które stale się zmienia, jest zróżnicowane w sposób nieodwracalny i daje się rozmaicie porządkować — nie uznaje siebie za dedukcyjny wywód logiczny lub nieuniknioną konkluzję wyprowadzoną z do- świadczenia osobistego czy eksperymentu naukowego, albo za wgląd w ukrytą naturę rzeczy lub transcendentalne objawienie. Własną koncepecję świata traktuje raczej j a k o przygodny wytwór wielu faktów. P r z y g o d n y w tym znaczeniu, iż koncepcja ta nie jest funkcją sposobu, w jaki świat istnieje, ale stanu, w jakim znajdują się poszczególne systemy oddziaływające wzajemnie na siebie w określonym czasie i miejscu. Koncepcja ta wymaga, aby istniało „coś" innego niż ona sama, innego niż sam proces pojmowania świata, ale nie pozwala ona o tym „czymś" niczego więcej powiedzieć czy pomyśleć — ani jednej cechy, którą można by wymienić, i żadnego sposobu, aby opisać, zanalizować lub wykorzystać jakąkolwiek jego właściwość — niczego, co byłoby niezależne od owego procesu pojmowania świata.7 Herrnstein Smith wątpi, aby wyznawany przez nią relatywizm mógł szerzej oddziaływać. W tej wyrafinowanej formie — z pewnością. Ale w formie zwulgaryzowanej przenika nie od dziś do kultury masowej i wpływa na potoczne zachowania ludzi i na styl życia. Może zresztą takie kreatywne rozumienie prawdy, nawet w odmianie uproszczonej, stanie się jeszcze jedną siłą napędową rozwiniętej cywilizacji. Ale czy w społeczeństwach dopiero wyzwalających się od zakłamanej rzeczywis- 7 B. Herrnstein Smith Contingencies of Value: Alternative Perspectives for Critical Theory, Cambridge, Mass. 1988, s. 183. http://rcin.org.pl 85 P O S T M O D E R N I Z M — CO TO I PO CO? tości relatywizm nie powiększy istniejącego chaosu norm i nie zakłóci elementarnego porządku myślowego? I oto dylemat: jeśli wierzę, że prawda jest nierelatywna, a jako wartość stoi na pierwszym miejscu, to muszę dążyć do niej nie bacząc na nic; ale jeśli idąc jej śladem przekonam się, że jest ona inna niż sądziłem, mniej nierelatywna, to czy dalej mam o tym mówić za wszelką cenę? Czy może powinienem kierować się potrzebami taktyki społecznej? W krajach autorytarnych instytucje odpowiedzialne za ład publiczny i wychowanie młodych mają prostą odpowiedź: obywateli trzeba chronić przed miazmatami myśli nowoczesnej. Oczywiście, odrzucamy to roz- wiązanie bez chwili wahania. Ale co w zamian? Richard Rorty namawia, aby nie przejmować się zbytnio negatywnymi z punktu widzenia społecznego treściami współczesnej literatury i filo- zofii. Chce, abyśmy z jednej strony kultywowali ekspresywne wartości osobowe, często nihilistyczne, a z drugiej pielęgnowali cnoty społeczne, zwłaszcza poczucie solidarności, i starali się chronić bliźnich przed cierpieniem. Czy jednak ja, jako istota prywatna, mam umacniać w sobie dyspozycje, które ja, j a k o istota publiczna, zmuszony byłbym potępić? Rozwiązanie Rorty'ego jest, zdaniem wielu, nie tyle rozwiązaniem, co uchylaniem się od niego, myślową konstrukcją pozwalającą zawiesić decyzję. Odnosząc się do pomysłu Rorty'ego z rezerwą, nie umiem jednak dostrzec żadnej innej przekonującej próby przezwyciężenia owej dwois- tości norm, tak dokuczliwej dla czytelników współczesnego piśmien- nictwa. Podejrzewam, że aby pogodzić te skłócone ze sobą wartości, potrzebna jest nie tyle teoria, co praktyka, zwłaszcza zaś to, co dawniej zwano roztropnością. I to zresztą wynika z książki Rorty'ego.8 8 Warto tu wspomnieć, dla równowagi, o jeszcze jednej autorce. Martha C. Nussbaum, filozof i filolog klasyczny, wychowana w tradycji filozofii analitycznej, od lat buduje swój program etyki w przekonaniu, że najlepszych wzorców percepcji moralnej dostarcza literatura. Broniąc umiarkowanego „esencjalizmu", tj. poglądu, że istnieją powszechne cechy gatunkowe, czyli natura ludzka (por. Human Functioning and Social Justice: In Defense of Aristotelian Essentializm, „Political Theory" Vol. 20, No. 2, May 1992), zaczynała od teatru greckiego, później zajęła się także pisarzami nowszymi. Wprawdzie przeprowadzana przez nią selekcja pozwalała omijać pisarzy najbardziej „niebezpiecz- nych", ale ostatnio udowodniła, że świetnie radzi sobie także z mistrzami postmodernizmu (por. Narrative Emotions: Beckett's Genealogy of Love, w jej książce Love's Knowledge: Essays on Philosophy and Literature, New York 1990). http://rcin.org.pl ZDZISŁAW ŁAPIŃSKI 86 Porównując stan humanistyki u nas i na Zachodzie, musimy przyznać, że długo pozostawaliśmy w sytuacji uprzywilejowanej. Humanistyka przez parę dziesięcioleci była polem, na którym rozgrywały się po- tyczki o całkiem wymiernych skutkach politycznych. Te dni minęły. Mamy poczucie, że nasze ręce krępuje sieć niewidzialnych nici. Słowa nie ważą tyle, ile ważyły w podjazdowej walce ze starym porządkiem. A jednocześnie nastroje powszechne są takie, że nawet nieważkie słowa potrafią wywołać złowrogie skutki. Można odnieść wrażenie, iż ludzie na trybunach mówią o prawdzie (swojej prawdzie) jako o czymś absolutnym, a swoim postępowaniem chcą nas przekonać, że prawda jest w ogóle pojęciem pustym. W tych okolicznościach szczypta świadomego siebie relatywizmu i jeszcze więk- sza dawka autoironii mogą działać z pożytkiem, jak trucizna zamieniona w szczepionkę. http://rcin.org.pl lapinski-postmod WA248_72852_P-I-2524_lapinski-postmodern work_kgpke2j6bbb5hncomqqnkzx3uu ---- BOOK REVIEWS 179 One Earth: Social and Environmental Justice Nicholas Low and Brendan Gleeson, 1999. Australian Conservation Foundation. 29 pp. 5 Parts. ISBN 0 85802 132 3. RRP No Cost. KELLI O'NEILL I Is it fair that some people live in a clean and healthy environment, while others live under oppressive, hazardous or ugly conditions? Is it fair that some reap the benefits of development, but fail to bear the cost of air, noise or water pollution resulting from the services they exploit? One Earth: Social and Environmental justice by Nicholas Low and Brendan Gleeson explores the connection between environmental responsibility and social justice by discussing the concepts of environmental and ecological justice. It is the second document in the Tela series published by the Australian Conservation Foundation. The Tela papers explore the relationships between the environment, society, the economy and the 21st century. Changes that are needed by the economy and society to achieve ecologically sustainability are examined. The series is aimed at decision makers, opinion leaders, educators and for general readership to spark debate on key environmental issues. According to Low and Gleeson environmental justice is the fair distribution of "good" (safe, attractive) and "bad" (hazardous, ugly) environments among people. It means the fair distribution of resources between people, ensuring that their basic needs are met. Ecological justice is the relationship between humans and the natural world and the connections they have with the environment. Perhaps the most pertinent issue presented IS that we cannot reasonably expect to make it a righteous, morally correct world simply by addressing environmental justice. The point is raised that it is anthropocentric to only consider the distribution of good and bad environments between people. What about other organisms? Don't they have rights to a healthy environment? In discussing this anthro- pocentric view the authors state that "public and private choices are today made within too narrow a band of the ethical spectrum" meaning that we need to expand our minds and have a greater sense of public morality to gain a complete account of our relationship with the environment. The critical question asked by the authors is whether we have to choose between "individualism with its potential for freedom and choice" or an "ecologically enlarged conception of the self in which we feel connected with and in some sense accountable to the whole of the natural world". A final theme of the paper discusses the need to increase public awareness about the environmental wealth our planet provides. By reducing greed and increasing personal ethic we begin to achieve environmental and ecological justice. There are three levels on which this enlargement can take place: The first involves the need to be inclusive of the natural world. The second suggests that the principles of justice need to be well defined. The third focuses on political justice in a global society. All organisms live in an unfair environment. However, most people seem unwilling, or are unaware of the need to change their habits to correct this unfairness. One Earth: Social and Environmental justice is a must read for everyone to expand their minds on the lack of justice in this world. The Tela papers are being distributed free to universities and are available on line at www. acfonline.org.au/publications/telalintro/htm 'School of Natural Sciences. Edith Cowan University, Joondalup, Western Australia. Australia 6027. work_kgxiiouvfrgiljboav77gqpsum ---- NimbusRomNo9L-Regu This is an Open Access document downloaded from ORCA, Cardiff University's institutional repository: http://orca.cf.ac.uk/115494/ This is the author’s version of a work that was submitted to / accepted for publication. Citation for final published version: Herman, Agatha, Goodman, Michael K.. and Sage, Colin 2018. Six questions for food justice [Commentary]. Local Environment 23 (11) , pp. 1075-1089. 10.1080/13549839.2018.1532401 file Publishers page: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/13549839.2018.1532401 Please note: Changes made as a result of publishing processes such as copy-editing, formatting and page numbers may not be reflected in this version. For the definitive version of this publication, please refer to the published source. You are advised to consult the publisher’s version if you wish to cite this paper. This version is being made available in accordance with publisher policies. See http://orca.cf.ac.uk/policies.html for usage policies. Copyright and moral rights for publications made available in ORCA are retained by the copyright holders. 1 This is a pre-copy-editing, author-produced PDF of a commentary paper accepted for publication in Local Environment, in the special issue New Spaces of Food Justice . Six Questions for Food Justice Agatha Herman (Cardiff University), Michael K. Goodman (University of Reading) and Colin Sage (University College Cork) Introduction In July 2014 the Food Justice: Knowing Food/Securing the Future workshop at the University of Reading, UK brought together over 60 academic and civil society delegates to discuss the contemporary state of food justice.1 While food is essential to the growth, development and health of human life, and to social well-being (Riches 2018), an array of contemporary challenges demonstrates that our food system does not ensure freedom from want and oppression, or environmental sustainability (Allen 2008). Indeed, when we consider the number of malnourished children that live in countries with food surpluses it becomes clear that a more equitable and healthy food system is substantively not an issue of production but, rather, of access and justice. Justice, in the context of food, has a variety of framings, including questions of rights, anti-poverty politics, community food security, distribution, political representation and collective self- determination (Levkoe 2006, Barnhill and Doggett 2018) Consequently, food justi e as a o ept, process, practice and outcome remains open to multiple interpretations (Gottlieb and Joshi 2010) with all the i he e t da ge s of ei g a e pt sig ifie (Heynen, Kurtz et al. 2012). Despite this, there is a utility and importance to wide, diverse engagements from a range of stakeholders in working through notions of food justice (Wekerle 2004). Indeed, this is mirrored by the number of alternative food o e e ts a oss the o ld fo usi g o the ultiple a s that a ial a d e o o i i e ualities are embedded within the production, distribution, and consumption of food (Alkon and Mares 2012: 348). These endeavour to explore the causes, symptoms, processes and outcomes of food justice and injustices (Agyeman and McEntree 2014) and recognize the need to address and challenge the socio- economic, political and ecological contexts and structures that have shaped food injustice (Alkon and Guthman 2017). 1 While we are representing the conversations, debates and discussions of the workshop, this material here remains ours and ours alone. 2 Food justi e is, the efo e, a iti al o ept oth fo s hola s a d fo people s e e da li ed ealities. For the former, it offers a conceptual framework to understand and analyse the broader structural i e uities that shape people s e pe ie es of food s ste s a d potentially contribute towards progressive policy development and social change (see, for example, Levkoe 2006, Sbicca 2012, Bradley and Galt 2014). For the latter, realising a more just food system means one in which everyone has a ess to suffi ie t, affo da le, health , ultu all app op iate food, a d – very importantly – respect and self-dete i atio (see also Dowler and O'Connor 2012, Bradley and Galt 2014: 173). Although food justice practices generally work through principles and ideals embodied within the broader struggle for social justice, the movement is not homogenous, especially when considering US2 experiences versus those in the UK (Food Ethics Council 2010; Kneafsey et al, this issue, Moragues- Faus 2017) and other parts of the globe (Besky 2015; Blake, this issue). The tensions and contestations reflecting the range of reformist to radical approaches, practices and rationalities (Brent, Schiavoni et al. 2015) were, and are, exemplified in our workshop and this special issue. Recent literature demonstrates the contemporary relevance of debates around food justice.3 Building on this foundational work and its normative politics, at the Reading workshop we wanted to take stock of these debates and ask questions about what else must and remains to be done across the scholarly and applied worlds. These concerns formed the basis of a set of dynamic interventions held during the workshop in which we—from our privileged positions—collectively considered, visualised and debated our understandings of the key contemporary challenges for food justice. All participants completed a worksheet in which they expressed their key challenge for food justice as an illustration and a short statement. These led into the development of project ideas to engage with the challenges identified and develop a set of cross-cutting common themes. A content analysis of the worksheets used deductive codes based on the latter while making space for others to inductively emerge. This iterative process grounds the six questions proposed here: 1. Is it possible to ensure fair provisioning with equitable access in food systems? 2. In what ways can we promote and enhance connections within food systems? 3. To what extent can existing collaborations and connections be built across scales? 4. How does food justice fit within wider drives towards social, economic and environmental justice? 5. How do we develop an effective critique of current food production strategies? 2 And particularly Californian perspectives on food justice, e.g. Alkon and Guthman, 2017b. 3 Particularly in the critical scholarship of Julie Guthman, Patricia Allen, Alison Hope Alkon, Justin Aygeman, Nik Heynan, Eric Holt- Giménez, Ryan Galt, Rachel Slocum, Molly Anderson, Anne Bellows, Liz Dowler, Moya Kneafsey, Melanie Bedore, Joshua Sbicca and Amy Trauger 3 6. Can food justice challenge the status quo of neoliberal capitalism? We also include a series of statements – interspersed and offset from the text in italics – from workshop participants that, in provocative ways, illustrate the variety of perspectives allowing individual voices to be heard. Food justice scholarship over the last 20 years has engaged with social movements and alternative practices, analysed inequalities and connected into broader areas of research and activism (Glennie and Alkon 2018). While some of the questions posed here may come as no surprise, that fact that they continue to be pertinent should alert us to both the progress that has been made and the struggles that remain ongoing and in need of critical attention. Moreover, while not exhaustive, they a t as a useful sto k take , fa ilitati g fu the de ate a ou d a s to eate o e just food s ste s. While we believe that the questions and statements in this paper represent the situated knowledges and experiences of those who attended the conference, the context of the latter is critical. As Glennie and Alkon (2018: 2) efle t esea h i te atio all has p o eeded at a diffe e t pa e, a d ith a diffe e t e phasis, tha the field of food justi e i the U ited “tates . Thus, discussions at the workshop were primarily grounded in our varied European experiences. While we hope this will help to broaden food justice debates beyond a predominantly US focus, we recognise that there are many other voices and perspectives with much to say on questions of food justice that are missing from this account. Indeed, one of the core issues that emerged from the workshop was the need to hear from, and publicly engage with, more marginal, unheard and underrepresented voices—particularly in Europe as austerity continues to deepen—many of whom face food poverty and injustice in their everyday lives: The main food justice challenge at the moment is to alleviate the black cloud of suffering hovering over millions of families and individuals unable to afford sufficient healthy food due to poverty. We e og ize, the , that this is a i pe fe t do u e t that o tai s statements or arguments that have been subject to analysis and, indeed, extensive critique elsewhere (see Alkon and Agyeman 2011, Cadieux and Slocum 2015, Slocum and Cadieux 2015, Slocum, Cadieux et al. 2016, Alkon and Guthman 2017, Moragues-Faus 2017) and much of this echoes through this special issue. Yet their inclusion is important as our intervention seeks to air these debates in ways that facilitate closer scrutiny and promote greater engagement and understanding with the key issues. While this paper represents the deliberations of a particular set of scholars and representatives from civil society, we recognize the limits of this work in terms of those who, at this moment, are systematically - if unintentionally - excluded. 4 The multidisciplinary and multi-sector nature of the Reading Workshop provided a wide-ranging platform of interests, experiences and values and meant that we did not always share a common view. However, the degree of relative consensus across this group suggests that the questions and issues raised here travel beyond disciplinary boundaries and warrant further consideration. Our hope is that the posing of questions rather than statements of aspiration will reveal new and continuing issues that have yet to be satisfactorily addressed from an alternative food movements and activism perspective. In this, our aim is to critically reflect on current literatures, bringing together cross-cutting issues to provoke further reflection on the future needs as well as the hopes, visions and potentials of food justice movements in a European and UK-focused context. 1. Is it possible to ensure fair provisioning with equitable access in food systems? Although food justice has been defined as the st uggle agai st a is , e ploitatio , a d opp essio taki g pla e ithi the food s ste that add esses i e ualit s oot auses oth ithi a d e o d the food hai (Hislop, 2014: 19 in Alkon 2014), the majority of research remains centred on individuals and relatively small, collective activist groups (e.g. Alkon and Guthman, 2017b). While this reveals the circumstances and everyday realities of food injustices, arguably this must be combined with a systems analysis, recognising growing corporate power and increasing consolidation and concentration across global food systems (Clapp and Scrinis 2016, Howard 2016, International Panel of Experts on Food Systems (IPES-Food) 2017). The manufacture, distribution and availability of rising volumes of cheap, nutrient deficient, energy dense foods are a vital part of the complex picture of food justice. For, with healthier food options regarded as less profitable (Stuckler and Nestle 2012), food corporations have strong financial incentives to promote highly refined, ultra-processed products. This is a feature of the global food system today, which is responsible for driving a nutrition transition – long established in the rich (OECD) countries – throughout middle and many low-income countries. As a consequence, health experts have been drawing attention with increasing urgency to rising levels of obesity accompanied by escalating rates of non-communicable diseases (NCD). For the food insecure especially, the steadily rising price of food has significantly outpaced the growth in household earnings. According to Woodall and Shannon (2018) since 2008 real consumer food prices have risen about three times faster than typical wages, with the benefits accruing to the biggest food, beverage and retail companies. It s ot a out p odu tio ut a ess to food Enough food is available globally, the halle ge is ho to e su e fai allo atio a d a oid aste 5 Holt-Giménez et al (2012) states that the world already produces enough food to feed 10 billion people. With the o ld s u e t populatio at . illio this suggests that it o ti ues to e po e t and inequality, rather than scarcity, which causes chronic hunger for 815 million people worldwide (HLPE 2014, FAO, IFAD et al. 2017). We say continues since Amartya Sen (1981: 1) commented over 30 years ago that starvation is the characteristic of some people not having enough food to eat. It is not the characteristic of there being not enough food . A well-documented consequence of this food supply challenge is the presence of both ends of the malnutrition spectrum – hunger and obesity – at the same time and even in the same space, a situatio also la elled al o su ptio (Sage 2013). Consequently, as Godfray et al (2010: 2769) have observed … e a ot e said to ha e a fu tio i g global food system when one in seven people today still do not have access to sufficient food, and an equal number are over-fed . People s li es ui ed y hu ge a d o esity: t o sides of the sa e oi Furthermore, access itself is an ecological issue, comprised of multiple, historical factors (Guthman 2012, Goodman, Carolan et al. 2014, Sage 2014). Wo k o food dese ts highlights that the contextual, structural constraints on tackling inequalities in food distribution exist in both developed and developing spaces; research on the foodways of low-income groups adds more nuanced depth to this by challenging the dominant narrative that low-income people do not have the desire, knowledge and/or means to eat healthier (Alkon, Block et al. 2013, Bowen, Elliott et al. 2014, Cairns and Johnston 2015) or to grow their own food (Kneafsey et al, this issue). There is significant knowledge about healthy food – growing and cooking it – amongst low income groups (Curran and Gonzalez 2011, Alkon, Block et al. 2013, Bradley and Galt 2014, Dixon 2014) but, as Dixon (2014: 178) comments, knowledge of ho to eat is ot al a s suffi ie t fo hoosi g to eat diffe e tl tha e do . Getting all the food produced in the world to all the world in a warming, fuel starved world The challenges posed by ensuring equitable access go beyond this scaled necessity to situate food justice in everyday lives and so recognise the inherent socio-cultural power relations that surround food. As the o e adi al , so ial justi e i a atio s of food justi e a gue, dispa ities i food a ess p o ide a i do i to a u h la ge s ste of a e a d lass elatio s (Brent, Schiavoni et al. 2015: 625); esse tial to the food justi e o e e t is a a al sis that e og izes the food s stem itself as a racial project that problematizes the influences of race and class on the production, distribution and o su ptio of food (Alkon and Agyeman 2011: 5). Food justice therefore connects into broader debates and geographies of power, capital, land and labour as well as the environment (Slocum, Cadieux et al. 2016). Indeed, the issue of food waste lies at the very heart of food justice considerations, particularly at a time of anthropogenic climate change and resource depletion (Evans 6 2014). For example, 6-10% of greenhouse gas emissions from developed countries are produced by growing food which is never consumed, while 250km3 of water are lost globally every year as a result of food wastage (HLPE 2014). The problems of food waste clearly translate into issues around equity and fairness in environmental as well as socio-political arenas. The main food justice challenge is that some people have more access to food and waste a lot, while others do not have enough With 33% of all food globally being wasted (HLPE 2014), food waste – whether caused by a surfeit of food, o su e o fusio o e use dates, poor storage or a lack of post-harvest transport – is clearly a significant factor impacting on food availability and equality of access. Yet recent years have witnessed growing political recognition and popular consciousness around the issue of food waste (Campbell, Evans et al. 2017) with attitudinal shifts from an environmental managerialism designed to reduce landfill costs toward a moral solution to the scandal of wasted food. That this coincided with the era of austerity, which followed in the wake of the 2008 financial crisis, and was accompanied by rising food prices, is not coincidental given that more frugal domestic budgeting became the norm. However, as Campbell et al (2017) observe, food waste has become a compelling new arena of political action that is ot si pl o all ad ut o e he e the ke ulp its – the major food retailers – moved quickly to reposition themselves as the solution. This has led to the rapid growth in number a d s ale of food a ki g ope atio s esta lished to pa t e ith etaile s i disposi g of food su pluses aste hile si ulta eousl sol i g the s ou ge of food po e t (Cloke, May et al. 2017, Gaithwaite 2017). Food justice activists and scholars have consequently had to respond to – and challenge – the dis ou se of sha i g , a i g a d suppo ti g as la ge o po atio s app op iate the language of solidarity in pursuing a business model that arguably reinforces an unsustainable and unfair food system. Moreover, the charitable redistribution of food surplus serves to conceal the extent of poverty, social exclusion and injustice and demonstrates the lack of a right to food security with dignity (Kenny and Sage 2018). Consequently, food justice is a multi-faceted issue situated within an interconnected network of social, political, economic, cultural and environmental justice challenges. While our discussion so far has been largely drawn in global terms we acknowledge that the problem of o e just food s ste s will only be achieved through concerted action across multiple scales, with the everyday and the local offering unique opportunities to (re)engage and (re)connect individuals and communities into food systems. 2. In what ways can we promote and enhance connections within food systems? 7 Disparities, disconnections and inequalities persist and grow One key challenge for food justice remains connecting people into food systems; with enhanced knowledge of the production, distribution and cooking of food, the transparency and accountability of these systems are strengthened. With such knowledge, people have an informed capability to hoose hat a d ho the ould like to o su e, a d to uestio a d halle ge the ads of food systems. The key question is how to enhance this access and connection to food. We are not trying to privilege the local because too tight a focus on this scale can lead to overly defensive and essentialised practices and attitudes (DuPuis and Goodman 2005). Furthermore, what is commonly understood as lo al food is, th ough its a ket positio i g, ta geted to a ds a spe ifi , highe -income, often white demographic making local food outlets such as farmers markets and delis exclusionary (Allen 2010, Guthman 2012, Bradley and Galt 2014), a community which arguably the Reading workshop also replicated. Nor, to be clear, are we suggesting an overt responsibilisation of poor or marginal – or of any – consumers. Rather, focusing on the particular enables more tightly defined actions as people are mobilised through specific events or relations that are of significance to them and their local communities; being grounded in responding to local needs can make food justice less abstract, distant, frustrating or disempowering than working at a larger scale (Allen 2010). However, remembering that international food systems are inherently multiscalar, a d the po e geo et ies (Massey 1999, Slocum, Cadieux et al. 2016) that this entails, the local must have these broader interconnections folded ithi it, othe ise food justi e st ategies o k a ou d the la ge food s ste i s all a s (Clendenning, Dressler et al. 2016: 170). Stop the institutionalisation of food. People should have adequate access to food which meets their social, financial and cultural needs. Rather than specifically critiquing the industrialisation of food systems, we identified the institutionalisation of food as a key means through which certain values, concepts and roles have become embedded and normalised within particular socio-economic spaces or organisations. This ossification acts to exclude particular others and preclude alternative formulations, discouraging people and communities from thinking about or doing food differently. These ideas around fostering po e f o ithi o e t i to oade d i es a ou d e po e e t, although this is ie ed disparagingly by food sovereignty movements (Holt-Gimenez and Wang 2011; Milner, this issue). While we do not wish to perpetuate the neoliberal logic that responsibility for welfare fundamentally rests with the individual, as seen through the examples discussed by Blake (this issue) and Alkon and Guthman (2017b), given the individualised nature of eating, people should be engaged – in appropriate and empowering ways (see Guthman 2008a, Guthman 2008b, Hayes-Conroy 2010, 8 Carolan 2011, Hayes-Conroy and Hayes-Conroy 2013, Figueroa and Alkon 2017) – to think about how they connect with food in order to build broader coalitions and communities of action. This is clearly difficult but, perhaps, a certain degree of normalisation of values is necessary in order to stabilise and coalesce these coalitions. However, every discourse already contains within it the potential for resistance and it is the loss of this radical potential through the institutionalisation and control of food by particular agents, such as corporations or state bodies, in particular ways which we might challenge. This is manifest in the tension apparent in many NGOs between their need for funding and their position as a structure of resistance, with Guthman (2006) stating that such flows of neoliberal capital into food movements depoliticise them by limiting the conceivable, the arguable, the fundable and the organisable. In some ways, this is est displa ed the o po atisatio of food po e t (Riches and Tarasuk 2014, Riches 2018) and where anti-hunger advocates have been accused of being complicit in the industrial hunger complex through their collaboration in surplus food redistribution (Fisher 2017). How to reconnect people to where food comes from and take ownership over the production of their own food, wherever they live? In discussions at the workshop, the role of an experiential element in enhancing connections emerged, with a physical act demanding a more active enrolment as well as helping to develop a dynamic sense of solidarity and community (Herman 2015, Herman 2016; Kneafesey et al, this issue). The literature is full of examples of community gardens, community farms, allotment associations, and cooking groups but, again, we argue that these need to be understood within the o te t of people s e e da , lived realities in order to enhance participation. There may be uiet ways in which people already engage with food (Smith and Jehlicka 2013) - such as how they involve their children or engage with homemade foods (Yotova, this issue) - which have had limited consideration from policymakers and academics, and that can be built upon. For example, Loo (2014) argues that how food justice is commonly defined omits recognition of the participatory inequalities in which material and distributive injustices are grounded. Therefore, personal transformations need to be related to broader political, economic, social and cultural change (Brent, Schiavoni et al. 2015). These drives need to be firmly situated within current cultural political economies, regulatory structures and relations of power. Their diversity, as well as that of alternative food initiatives themselves, must also be acknowledged. These (re)connections cannot happen in isolation at the local scale but must contain a broader acknowledgement of the relationalities that living in a globalised world entail. Given the often-lengthy commodity networks of food products we therefore must also support the rights and needs of the 9 other stakeholders within these chains in order to build extensive and meaningful collaborations and consensus. 3. To what extent can existing collaborations and connections be built across scales? All together at the table: Northern and Southern producers, business, transportation, retailing, consumers and nature! As Allen (2010: 297) a gues, … o o e ould a gue that food-system localization can undo the i e uities eated histo ies of olo ialis , i pe ialis a d eoli e alizatio . In order to address these igge st u tu es a d ideologies e the efo e eed to o i e lo a o is ith igge pi tu e collective solidarity. Getting communities affected by food poverty and austerity to speak for/by themselves and organise for power Allen (2008: 160) otes that si e the ag ifood s ste is socially organised, problems are the product of so ial hoi es, e odied i t aditio s, i stitutio s, a d legal a d e o o i st u tu es . Although, as mentioned above, the latter can lead to these ideas and p a ti es e o i g o alised a d lo ked i , o e e e og ise that i justi e is a o se ue e of social forces, we can acknowledge that we ha e, o a de elop, the apa ilit to do othe ise (Sen 1999). This then opens up the terrain – albeit within certain socio-economic bounds and for certain powerful actors – enabling us to develop the power to see possibilities and opportunities for difference and change. Building on individualistic, pragmatic initiatives at local scale to develop overtly political action carried out by collectives of food justice activists However, not everyone in global food systems has the agency to make other choices. Since we recognise the interconnected nature of contemporary global food systems, this demands a holistic understanding of how injustices are experienced throughout networks and across the myriad human and more-than-human actants who engage with them. The industrialisation and institutionalisation of food has acted to fetishize our relations with it, meaning that food justice movements, at least in the US, tend to focus on local and urban issues of consumption and distribution (Clendenning, Dressler et al. 2016) rather than overtly confronting the political economies of food production (see, however, McEntree 2011, Brent, Schiavoni et al. 2015, Eaton 2017, Harrison 2017). Nonetheless, the common ground across developed and developing spaces for those marginalised in the modern food system highlights the potential opportunities for international networks and solidarity (Clendenning, Dressler et al. 2016). Recent developments in ICTs, alternative trading systems such as Fair Trade, academic a d popula follo the thi g dis ussio s (Cook 2006) and engagements with food at the local scale 10 can work together to enhance our awareness of the challenges of domination, exploitation and coercion within food systems, and make connections between the various network nodes possible. Not just one but many worlds are at stake (framing food in ethical terms can over-write this politics of difference) As Bradley and Galt (2014: 173) state food justi e is a out espe t a d self-determination in all phases of food p odu tio , e ha ge, a d o su ptio . The efo e, if e a t to a oid al a s ha i g a o al remainder to our food choices – good in animal welfare versus poor in food miles; locally produced and distributed versus not supporting marginalised overseas producers; cheap food versus exploited labour – then we must develop connections between the various worlds in food systems in order to build better knowledges of each other, our needs and our rights. What this suggests, then, is the need to broaden food justice movements both spatially and in terms of their political and socio-economic engagements. Food justice is obligation, responsibility and reciprocity from grassroots to small farmers Having positioned the necessity for global collaborations, we now turn to a more practical question: how can food justice be achieved? While we were all agreed that this was an essential requirement for a just food future, there was also recognition that achieving this will be neither an easy nor a straightforward task. How do we visualise and revalorize low and unpaid work in food networks and build collective methodologies and more egalitarian movements? De elopi g asso iatio al po e ith as a olle ti e ought togethe th ough food is halle gi g. Although Allen s (2008: 159) statement that o othe pu li issue is as a essi le to people i thei daily lives as that of food justice. Everyone – regardless of age, gender, ethnicity, or social class – eats. We a e all i ol ed, a d e a e all i pli ated resonates, how do we enable all voices in food networks to be heard? The women and girls doing unpaid, subsistence work; the small farmers who cannot afford Fairtrade certification; the non-unionised food chain workers; the microbes and pathogens that influence yields; the active lives of plants and animals – all have stories even if they have no or limited capability to share them. Issues of food justice thus connect into broader social justice debates around, amongst others, power, access, household finances, gender equality, education, the valorisation of knowledge and cultural traditions and identities (as discussed by Milner and Yotova, both this issue). To overcome injustices throughout the food chain we need to start treating people as citizens NOT consumers, and address food inequalities at various scales 11 Following Levkoe (2006: 90), we agree that food is o e tha just a othe o odit a d people a e o e tha just o su e s . Ho e e , while the rise of the citizen-consumer (Wheeler 2012) recognises citizenship as active, accountable and acknowledges that there are multiple ways in which to participate in the polity, the citizen- o su e is eithe passi e o full i o t ol (Jubas 2007: 250). Furthermore, this is grounded in the rhetoric of personal choice, requiring the citizen to have pu hasi g po e , hi h is u e e l dist i uted i so iet a d de ol es espo si ilit do to the individual level. While this acts as a reminder that there are multiple ways of being political, demonstrating solidarity and challenging society to better itself (Barnett, Cloke et al. 2011, Guthman and Brown 2016), we need to move beyond the confines imposed by the citizen-consumer to open up alternative routes of communication and connection across the scales, recognising the translocal and transnational nature of food justice (Wekerle 2004, Sage 2014). Collaborations and connections must be embedded in an expansive view of the social to establish a holistic understanding of the myriad actants and relationships underpinning the development of just food practices and systems. In Herman (2016) the forest was a key actant in supporting the resilience of Finnish farms; in Ferguson and the Northern Rivers Landed Histories Research Group (2016) soil was an important ally in struggles for sustainable food systems; and in Williams and Holt-Giménez (2017) land was central to food activism. A more-than-human approach moves food justice from being a process of individual responsibilisation to being grounded in an emergent and relational community. Therefore, rather than simply adopting consumption as the only way to engage or, indeed, o pletel e ludi g it f o people s dail li es, e eed to utilise ultiple and diverse strategies to build connections across different contexts, requirements and motivations. How we do this in the specific context of food justice remains an ongoing and open question but must be balanced within broader social and environmental justice movements. 4. How does food justice fit within wider drives towards social, economic and environmental justice? Food justice is a out o e tha food, it s a out li ki g food issues to othe a d oade sustai a ility issues. Agyeman (2013: 59) o e ts that food has e o e o e of the ke a e as in which conflicts around justi e a d sustai a ilit ha e pla ed out… food has also lo g ee a d i e of so ial o e e ts . This can be seen in histories and discussions of the Black Panthers in the USA (Heynen 2009), the development of community farms (Levkoe 2006, Curran and Gonzalez 2011, Bradley and Galt 2014), race and class (Slocum and Saldanha 2013), farmers markets (Alkon and Norgaard 2009, Alkon and Mares 2012), advocacy and praxis for healthy food (Freudenberg, McDonough et al. 2011, Sbicca 12 2012) and food banks (Greenberg and Greenberg 2010, Tarasuk, Dachner et al. 2014, Farahbakhsh 2015, Loopstra 2015, Gonzalez-Torre and Coque 2016). With all these diverse spaces, actants and practices it is unsurprising that food justice movements have struggled to bridge the many diverse concerns within the agrifood system (Sbicca 2012), let alone the arena of social justice more broadly, and so remain open to many interpretations (Gottlieb and Joshi 2010, Brent, Schiavoni et al. 2015). Yet, as we indicated above, it is clear that justice in terms of food is co-constitutive with many other drives for justice, whether cultural, political, economic, social or environmental. Indeed, given the importance of parallel discussions in the field of sustainable consumption, questions of defining human needs and necessities for equitable well-being (Gough 2017) must involve questions of food justice. Food justice challenge: solidarity with related social justice struggles for positive change and accountability The particular, micro-scale nature of our own food interactions means that any changes in access, price, distribution or quality can have a direct impact on more people than other socio-economic changes. As Barnett (2010) efle ts, a a e ess a d a al sis of justi e ofte o es f o e pe ie es o i tuitio s of i justi e ; a spe ifi e e t can mobilise individuals and communities to challenge the broader structures and relations that have triggered this change in their foodways. As such, food can build a stronger community through breaking down individualism and seclusion (Levkoe 2006). This is ot to sa that food is ot as politi all e t e hed, et o ked, histo i all ou d, a d tied to nature as othe esou es e ui ed fo hu a su i al ut the e is likel o othe esou e e ui ed fo hu a su i al that is as ultu all ou d… (Agyeman and McEntree 2014: 216-217) and so has the apa it to uild a ultu e of u it i di e sit (Sbicca 2012: 465). The geographical scope of food systems – joining diverse people and places – and conceptual focus on food and the environment, health, labour, hunger, production and access (Gottlieb and Joshi 2010; Blake and Milner, both this issue) opens up more radical critiques of capitalism, racism, patriarchy, authority and power: Without e o o i , politi al a d so ial e uality e a t a hie e food justi e. Although there are multiple ways in which different people understand and practice eating, this deg ee of sha ed e pe ie e a gua l ope s up i do s i to othe s li es that e otio all eso ate with the viewer and allow us to e o e ale t to st u tu al inequities that deprive individuals of the oppo tu it to e ade uatel ou ished (Dixon 2014: 183). The concept of food justice is itself framed around the need for systemic change to address inequities within food systems and, by 13 tackling questions of mobilisation and strategies, it connects into broader discussions around democracy, citizenship, civil society and social movements (Wekerle 2004). Fa e s a d othe food o ke s do t get a fai age fo thei o k a d a y li e i food po e ty themselves While workers are increasingly visible (see Harrison 2008, Brown and Getz 2011, Alkon 2014) the literatures on food poverty have focused largely on consumer experiences and practices with debates around food access highlighting the complexity of decision-making processes for low-income groups (Bowen, Elliott et al. 2014, Chen 2016, Daniel 2016, Baumann, Szabo et al. 2017). Further, in spite of food desert literatures, Alkon et al (2013) conclude that the key barrier to obtaining desired foods is not lack of proximity or knowledge but lack of income. Purchasing food is part of a wider nexus of choices over, amongst others, accommodation, heating, transport, clothing and healthcare. Even though the UK and others are slowly recovering from the recession caused by the 2007/08 financial crisis and continuing austerity policies, wages are stagnating (O'Connor 2014) and one in five Britons live below the official national relative poverty line (Department for Work and Pensions 2017). This is reflected in the rise in demand for foodbanks; one leading UK provider, The Trussell Trust, provided over 1.3 million emergency food supplies in 2017/18, which is a nearly four-fold increase over the last five years (The Trussell Trust 2018). Therefore, stories of food can reveal much bigge a ati es of do i a e, e ploitatio , i ilisatio …a d, o asio all , it ust e said, hope a d diffe e e (Cook 2006: 659); by bringing together coalitions through particular contexts these large issues become more manageable, with individuals feeling that they can make a difference (Levkoe 2006). However, the other side to demonstrating these needs for justice is the concurrent requirement to outline both alternatives to, and pathways of transformation from, current systems, beliefs and practices in order to motivate action through providing a hopeful and different future. 5. How do we develop an effective critique of current food production strategies? While the workshop delegates agreed that local, organic, Fair Trade and community food production systems all have their benefits, debate continues as to whether these can offer a viable means to feed the global population of 10.7 billion projected by the UN by 2075 (UN Population Division 2017). Given that the existing system already produces enough to feed 1.5 times the current global population (Holt-Gimenez, Shattuck et al. 2012), this suggests some capacity to engage with more socially and environmentally responsible alternatives. Nevertheless, availability and price continue to strongly shape food access and choices, and opponents of alternative agricultural strategies argue that these 14 cannot deliver across all of these challenges. However, recent studies have challenged this hegemonic wisdom (Seufort, Ramankutty et al. 2012), opening up the terrain to offer effective critiques of current food production through acknowledging that alternatives are viable options that can operate at much larger scales than currently exist. Despite continuing debate around the relative merits of agroecology, conventional farming and smart- agriculture in the literature (Holmes 2010, Azadi, Talsma et al. 2011, Dibden, Gibbs et al. 2011), a general disquiet was felt amongst the delegates towards some of the practices of industrial agriculture with its focus on production maximisation: Global food distribution – moves food – depletes soil – cheap food – wasted – no skills in food Again, certain discourses of food were felt to have been institutionalised with a focus on a corporate- led model of agriculture, GMOs and profit over people leading to environmental and social degradation. Concerns around the commodification of life and relationships emphasized feelings of alienation and disconnection, with a general consideration that food needs to be recognised and understood as a commons resource, not just another commodity (Vivero Pol 2017). Fundamentally, this reflects a broader critique of the neoliberal capitalist, corporatist systems that have powerfully incubated and institutionalised this hegemony. While this may have become so normalised that it is difficult to think beyond (Gibson-Graham 2006), recognising that alternatives can address the global challenge of sufficient, affordable, healthy and culturally appropriate food is an important first step in considering: Ho to syste ati ally idge the gap et ee su plus a d eed hilst ai tai i g effi ie t production The idea of effi ie is pe siste t a d so, while there are many critiques of industrial agriculture, proponents can argue that it clearly does produce more than enough to feed the world despite its environmental downsides. The goods a d ads of o e tional agriculture are therefore known, defined and so understandable; as such they offer scope for improvements through research and de elop e t. I o t ast, alte ati es ep ese t u k o s ofte i te s of oth thei ideologies and outcomes. Therefore, the public may position itself as ethically virtuous but latent conservatism, social inertia and socio-economic inequality means that the value-knowledge-action gap remains when engaging with food injustices. Fu the o e, u h of the alte ati e food o ement continues to be defined by white, middle- lass i di iduals, o ga isatio s a d i stitutio s (Agyeman and McEntree 2014: 213), and this class-based perception, and arguably reality, of the types of people who do food diffe e tl potentially restricts its broader appeal (but see Figueroa and Alkon 2017). 15 Perceptions that doing food differently are niche and trendy (and a matter of taste?) This remains a critical hurdle which exponents of alternative food strategies – whether reworking or revolutionising conventional agri-food systems – need to address. Arguments over the negative environmental, labour, health and social consequences of industrial agriculture have a long history but market alternatives have remained relatively niche, e lusi e a d p e ious (Guthman 2003). The challenge to offering an effective critique is therefore grounded in the ongoing question of how to, as Bradley and Herrera (2016) reflect, decolonise food justice movements. Again, this emphasizes how an empirical focus on food speaks to wider social issues and so we end with a final reflection on whether food justice can be used to challenge long ingrained ideologies and structures. 6. Can food justice challenge the status quo of neoliberal capitalism? Fundamentally, food justice comes down to questions of power and a fundamental challenge to the domination and coercion wielded by food corporations over marginalised stakeholders, i.e. those who need to buy food to live but who lack resources. How can those who experience multiple deprivations—and their cooperative allies who seek to work with and be led by them—be empowered to collectively achieve these goals (Rowlands 1997, Allen 2003, Alkon and Guthman 2017b)? Making (global) capitalism work for me! Changing from within In challenging such structural constraints to more equitable and just relations within food systems, food justice movements must question broader neoliberal and capitalist hegemonies. But how might they embark on these processes when food movements are critiqued for opposing neoliberalism in their discourses while e a i g it th ough thei p a ti es of a ket-as- o e e t (Alkon 2014)? Alkon (2014: 31) a gues that a fo us o o su ptio a o st ai ou olle tive imaginaries of what ki ds of so ial ha ges a e ought a out – hat a e ues of ha ge ould e ope ed to us if e also sa ou sel es as itize s, eigh o s, o just hu a s (Werkheiser and Noll 2014: 204)? ‘e og isi g food s apa it to a t as a olle ti isi g fo e ibid) makes space to e pa d the politi s of the possi le . The particularities of our engagements enables food both to bring people together through a degree of commonality while still providing powerful counter-narratives that question accepted norms: Redistribute power from retailers toward producers Consolidation of the food systems; inequitable capital; power distribution along the supply system; the lack of illusion of choice Why should retailers hold a disproportionate degree of power? Would the food sector not benefit from more security and stability for all producers? What kind of alliances are possible? Consolidation 16 of food systems may improve efficiency but this does not necessarily translate into nutritional security. Of course, one condition that made corporate control over the global food system possible has been the e e ge e of the i diffe e t state . Declare hunger illegal! As Riches (2018) carefully outlines, under human rights conventions and protocols governments are obliged to ensure domestic compliance to respect, protect and fulfil the right to food of their populations. Yet in practice – with broken social safety nets, regressive income distribution and an increasingly dysfunctional industrial food system – most OECD states display utter disinclination to enshrine a right to food into national law or to accept public accountability for their failings. Until such time as effective joined up public policy prevails over private philanthropy and charitable food handouts, then food justice will be overshadowed by consumer sovereignty concerns. These issues are common in debates within alternative food movements but more purchase could be achieved through explicitly utilising the moral and ethical connotations and resonances of food justice. Food is not just an economic conundrum, a logistical concern or a way to achieve political resonance but a very real and material issue that affects millions throughout the world on a daily basis. Concluding Reflections We strongly believe that food justice remains a vital political objective for millions of people, and one that offers an important axis for mobilisation within broader socio-economic and environmental justice struggles. Through these six questions – derived as they have been from our particularly European context – we have outlined some of the key challenges facing food justice movements as they seek to move forwards, which include issues around feasibility, viability, mobilisation and ethics. These highlight areas both for further research and activism, which must work together if we want to better understand different foodways, and so build stronger and more resilient connections between diverse communities. Within the research element of this, more attention needs to be paid to the continuing gaps in the US-centric literatures, which have a predominant focus on the racial and class- based inequalities experienced by consumers, a task the papers in this special issue have begun to address. More research is needed to give space to other voices – those marginalised by gender, sexuality, disability and age as well as those suffering from a lack of access, and ability to access, healthy, high quality and tasty foods – in a global and holistic view of agri-food systems, which acknowledges too the role and agency of non-human actants. Within this we must always remember to question the power relations and contexts of food justice – where is it coming from? In the context of the workshop we were overwhelmingly coming from 17 European, white, middle-class, academic, third-sector backgrounds, which clearly shapes what we know and what we can know. It seems, perhaps, a little ironic that we call for a greater diversity of voices, and for those marginalised within food systems to be re-centralised, when we have not achieved this even within our workshop. Nevertheless, this points to the continuous and always in progress nature of such movements in search of justice and the challenges they face in terms of mobilisation and participation. Following Milner (this issue) and Loo (2014), we agree that a broader, postcolonial and participatory understanding of food justice must be cultivated in order to move beyond the local, distributive issues in which it often becomes mired; we need to make space for the broader, more-than-human connections, interactions and knowledges necessary to shape a o e e t that is itself just . Pe haps e eed to o e a a f o the conceptual baggage of food justi e a d i stead a k o ledge that e a e si pl t i g to o eptualise, o te tualise a d a hie e justice in food systems. Acknowledgements Many thanks to all of the participants and speakers at the Reading workshop and to David Evans for commenting critically on a much earlier version of this intervention. All of the arguments, analysis and interpretations in this intervention are ours and ours alone. References Agyeman, J. (2013). Introducing Just Sustainabilities: policy, planning, and practice. London, Zed Books. Agyeman, J. and J. McEntree (2014). "Moving the Field of Food Justice Forward through the Lens of Urban Political Ecology." Geography Compass 8(3): 211-220. Alkon, A. H. (2014). "Food Justice and the Challenge to Neoliberalism." Gastronomica 14(2): 27-40. Alkon, A. H. and J. Agyeman (2011). Cultivating Food Justice: Race, Class, and Sustainability. Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Alkon, A. H., D. Block, K. Moore, C. Gillis, N. DiNuccio and N. Chavez (2013). "Foodways of the Urban Poor." Geoforum 48: 126-135. Alkon, A. H. and J. Guthman, Eds. (2017). The New Food Activism: opposition, cooperation, and collective action, University of California Press. Alkon, A. H. and J. Guthman (2017b). Introduction. The new food activism: opposition, cooperation, and collective action A. H. Alkon and J. Guthman. Berkeley, University of California Press: 1-30. Alkon, A. H. and T. M. Mares (2012). "Food Sovereignty in US Food Movements: radical visions and neoliberal constraints." Agriculture and Human Values 29(347-359). 18 Alkon, A. H. and K. M. Norgaard (2009). "Breaking the Food Chains: an investigation of food justice activism." Sociological Inquiry 79(3): 289-305. Allen, J. (2003). Lost Geographies of Power. Oxford, Blackwell Publishers Ltd. Allen, P. (2008). "Mining for Justice in the Food System: perceptions, practices, and possibilities." Agriculture and Human Values 25: 157-161. Allen, P. (2010). "Realizing Justice in Local Food Systems." Cambridge Journal of Regions, Economy and Society 3: 295-308. Azadi, H., N. Talsma, P. Ho and K. Zarafshani (2011). "GM Crops in Ethiopia: a realistic way to increase agricultural performance?" Trends in Biotechnology 29(1): 6-8. Barnett, C. (2010). "Geography and Ethics: justice unbound." Progress in Human Geography 35(2): 246-255. Barnett, C., P. Cloke, N. Clarke and A. Malpass (2011). Globalizing responsibility: The political rationalities of ethical consumption. London, Blackwell. Barnhill, A. and T. Doggett (2018). "Food Ethics I: food production and food justice." Philosophy Compass 13: 1-13. Baumann, S., M. Szabo and J. Johnston (2017). "Understanding the food preferences of people of low socioeconomic status." Journal of Consumer Culture. Besky, S. (2015). "Agricultural Justice, Abnormal Justice? An Analysis of Fair Trade's Plantation Problem." Antipode 47(5): 1141-1160. Bowen, S., S. Elliott and J. Brenton (2014). "The Joy of Cooking?" Contexts 13(3): 20-25. Bradley, K. and R. E. Galt (2014). "Practicing Food Justice at Dig Deep Farms & Produce, East Bay Area, California: self-determination as a guiding value and intersections with foodie logics." Local Environment 19(2): 172-186. Bradley, K. and H. Herrera (2016). "Decolonizing Food Justice: naming, resisting, and researching colonizing forces in the movement." Antipode 48(1): 97-114. Brent, Z. W., C. M. Schiavoni and A. Alonso-Fradejas (2015). "Contextualising Food Sovereignty: the politics of convergence among movements in the USA." Third World Quarterly 36(3): 618-635. Brown, S. and C. Getz (2011). Farmworker Food Insecurity and the Production of Hunger in California. Cultivating Food Justice: race, class, and sustainability. A. H. Alkon and J. Agyeman. Cambridge, MA, MIT Press: 121-146. Cadieux, K. and R. Slocum (2015). "What does it mean to do food justice?" Journal of Political Ecology 22: 1-26. Cairns, K. and J. Johnston (2015). Food and femininity. London, Bloomsbury. Campbell, H., D. Evans and A. Murcott (2017). "Measurability, austerity and edibility: Introducing waste into food regime theory." Journal of Rural Studies 51: 168-177. 19 Carolan, M. (2011). Embodied Food Politics. Aldershot, Ashgate. Che , W. . "F o Ju k Food to T eats . Ho Po e t “hapes Fa il Food P a ti es." Food, Culture & Society 19(1): 1-20. Clapp, J. and G. Scrinis (2016). "Big Food, nutritionism and corporate power." Globalizations 14(4): 578-595. Clendenning, J., W. H. Dressler and C. Richards (2016). "Food Justice or Food Sovereignty? Understanding the Rise of Urban Food Movements in the USA." Agriculture and Human Values 33: 165-177. Cloke, P., J. May and A. Williams (2017). "The geographies of food banks in the meantime." Progress in Human Geography 41(6): 703-726. Cook, I. (2006). "Geographies of Food: following." Progress in Human Geography 30(5): 655-666. Curran, C. J. and M.-T. Gonzalez (2011). "Food Justice as Interracial Justice: urban farmers, community organizations and the role of government in Oakland, California." The University of Miami Inter- American Law Review 43(1): 207-232. Daniel, C. (2016). "Economic constraints on taste formation and the true cost of healthy eating." Social Science & Medicine 148: 34-41. Department for Work and Pensions (2017). Households Below Average Income: 1994/95 to 2015/16. Westminster, Department for Work and Pensions. Dibden, J., D. Gibbs and C. Coklin (2011). "Framing GM Crops as a Food Security Solution." Journal of Rural Studies 29: 59-70. Dixon, B. A. (2014). "Learning to See Food Justice." Agriculture and Human Values 31: 175-184. Dowler, E. and D. O'Connor (2012). "Rights Based Approaches to Addressing Food Poverty and Food Insecurity in Ireland and UK." Social Science & Medicine 74(1): 44-51. DuPuis, E. M. and D. Goodman (2005). "Should we go home to eat?: Towards a reflexive politics of localism." Journal of Rural Studies 21(3): 359-371. Eaton, E. (2017). How Canadian Farmers Fought and Won the Battle against GM Wheat. The new food activism: opposition, cooperation, and collective action A. H. Alkon and J. Guthman. Berkeley, University of California Press: 55-80. Evans, D. (2014). Food Waste: home consumption, material culture and everyday life. London, Bloomsbury. FAO, IFAD, UNICEF, WFP and WHO (2017). The State of Food Security and Nutrition in the World: building resilience for peace and food security. Rome, FAO. Farahbakhsh, J. (2015). "How do Student Clients of a University Based Food Bank Cope with Food Insecurity?" Canadian Journal of Dietetic Practice and Research 76(4): 200-203. 20 Ferguson, H. and the Northern Rivers Landed Histories Research Group (2016). "More than Something to Hold the Plants Up: soil as a non-human ally in the struggle for food justice." Local Environment 21(8): 956-968. Figueroa, M. and A. H. Alkon (2017). Cooperative Social Practices, Self-Determination, and the Struggle for Food Justice in Oakland and Chicago. The new food activism: opposition, cooperation, and collective action A. H. Alkon and J. Guthman. Berkeley, University of California Press: 206-231. Fisher, A. (2017). Big Hunger. Cambridge, MA, MIT Press. Food Ethics Council (2010). Food Justice: the report of the Food and Fairness Inquiry. Brighton, Food Ethics Council. Freudenberg, N., J. McDonough and E. Tsui (2011). "Can a Food Justice Movement Improve Nutrition and Health? A Case Study of the Emerging Food Movement in New York City." Journal of Urban Health 88(4): 623-636. Gaith aite, K. . "I feel I gi i g so ethi g a k to so iet : Co st u ti g the a ti e itize and responsibilising foodbank use." Social Policy and Society 16(2): 283-292. Gibson-Graham, J. K. (2006). A post-capitalist politics. Minneapolis, University of Minnesota Press. Glennie, C. and A. H. Alkon (2018). "Food Justice: cultivating the field." Environmental Research Letters 13: 1-13. Godfray, H. C. J., I. R. Crute, L. Haddad, D. Lawrence, J. F. Muir, N. Nisbett, J. Pretty, S. Robinson, C. Toulmin and R. Whiteley (2010). "The Future of the Global Food System." Philosophical Transactons of the Royal Society B 365(1554): 2769-2777. Gonzalez-Torre, P. L. and J. Coque (2016). "How is a Food Bank Managed? Different Profiles in Spain." Agriculture and Human Values 33(1): 89-100. Goodman, M. K., M. Carolan, A. Lopez-Carr, D. Lopez-Carr, L. Jarosz, P. McMichael and C. Sage (2014). "The Ecologies of Food Power: Environment and Food Book Symposium." Sociologia Ruralis 54(1): 94- 115. Gottlieb, R. and A. Joshi (2010). Food Justice. Cambridge, MA, The MIT Press. Gough, I. (2017). "Recomposing consumption: defining necessities for sustainable and equitable well- being." Philosophical Transactons of the Royal Society A 375. Greenberg, M. and G. Greenberg (2010). "Food Pantries, Poverty, and Social Justice." American Journal of Public Health 100(11): 2021-2022. Guthman, J. (2003). "Fast Food/Organic Food: reflexive tastes and the making of 'yuppie chow'." Social and Cultural Geography 4(1): 45-58. Guthman, J. (2006). "Neoliberalism and the making of food politics in California." Geoforum 39: 1171- 1183. Guthman, J. (2008a). "Bringing good food to others: investigating the subjects of alternative food practice." Cultural Geographies 15(4): 431-447. 21 Guthman, J. (2008b). ""If They Only Knew": Color Blindness and Universalism in California Alternative Food Institutions." Professional Geographer 60(3): 387-397. Guthman, J. (2012). "Doing Justice to Bodies? Reflections on Food Justice, Race, and Biology." Antipode. Guth a , J. a d “. B o . "Midas ot-so-golden touch: on the demise of methyl iodide as a soil fumigant in California." Journal of Environmental Policy and Planning 18(3): 324-341. Harrison, J. (2017). Taking a Different Tack: Pesticide Regulatory-Reform Activism in California. The new food activism: opposition, cooperation, and collective action A. H. Alkon and J. Guthman. Berkeley, University of California Press: 31-54. Harrison, J. L. (2008). "Lessons Learned from Pesticide Drift: a call to bring production agriculture, farm labor, and social justice back into agrifood research and activism." Agriculture and Human Values 25(2): 163-167. Hayes-Conroy, A. (2010). "Feeling Slow Food: visceral fieldwork and empathetic research relations in the alternative food movement." Geoforum 41(734-742). Hayes-Conroy, A. and J. Hayes-Conroy (2013). Doing Nutrition Differently: critical approaches to diet and dietary intervention. Farnham, Ashgate. Herman, A. (2015). "Enchanting Resilience: relations of care and people-place connections in agriculture." Journal of Rural Studies 42: 102-111. Herman, A. (2016). "'More-than-human' resilience(s)? Enhancing Community in Finnish Forest Farms." Geoforum 69: 34-43. Heynen, N. (2009). "Bending the Bars of Empire from Every Ghetto for Survival: the Black Panther Party's Radical Antihunger Politics of Social Reproduction and Scale." Annales of the Association of American Geographers 99(2): 406-422. Heynen, N., H. E. Kurtz and A. Trauger (2012). "Food Justice, Hunger and the City." Geography Compass 6(5): 304-311. HLPE (2014). Food Losses and Waste in the Context of Sustainable Food Systems. Rome, Committee on World Food Security. Holmes, B. (2010). "Veggieworld: why eating greens won't save the planet." New Scientist(14 July). Holt-Gimenez, E., A. Shattuck, M. Altieri, H. Herren and S. Gliessman (2012). "We Already Grow Enough Food for 10 Billion People...and Still Can't End Hunger." Journal of Sustainable Agriculture 36(6): 595- 598. Holt-Gimenez, E. and Y. Wang (2011). "Reform or Transformation? The Pivotal Role of Food Justice in the U.S. Food Movement." Race/Ethnicity 5(1): 83-102. Howard, P. (2016). Concentration and Power in the Food System: who controls what we eat? London, Bloomsbury. 22 International Panel of Experts on Food Systems (IPES-Food) (2017). Too Big to Feed: Exploring the impacts of mega-mergers, consolidation and concentration of power in the agri-food sector. www.ipes-food.org Jubas, K. (2007). "Conceptual Con/fusion in Democratic Societies: understandings and limitations of consumer citizenship." Journal of Consumer Culture 7(2): 231-254. Kenny, T. and C. Sage (2018). Food surplus as charitable provision: obstacles to re-introducing food as a commons. Routledge Handbook of Food as a Commons. J. L. V. Pol, T. Ferrando, O. d. Schutter and U. Mattei. Abingdon, Routledge. Levkoe, C. Z. (2006). "Learning Democracy through Food Justice Movements." Agriculture and Human Values 23: 89-98. Loo, C. (2014). "Towards a More Participative Definition of Food Justice." Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 27: 787-809. Loopstra, R. (2015). "Food Bank Usage is a Poor Indicator of Food Insecurity: insights from Canada." Social Policy and Society 14(3): 443-455. Massey, D. (1999). Imagining Globalization: power-geometries of time-space. Global Futures: Migration, Environment and Globalization. A. Brah, M. J. Hickman and M. a. G. Mairtin. Basingstoke, Palgrave Macmillan: 27-44. McEntree, J. (2011). Realizing rural food justice: Divergent locals in the northeastern United States. Cultivating Food Justice. A. H. Alkon and J. Agyeman. Cambridge, MA, The MIT Press: 239-260. Moragues-Faus, A. (2017). "Problematising justice definitions in public food security debates: Towards global and participative food justice." Geoforum 84(95-106). O'Connor, S. (2014). Wage Growth Feeble as UK Economy Recovers. Financial Times. Riches, G. (2018). Food Bank Nation: poverty, corporate charity and the right to food. London, Routledge. Riches, G. and V. Tarasuk (2014). Canada: thirty years of food charity and public policy neglect. First World Hunger Revisited: food charity or the right to food? G. Riches and T. Silvasti. London, Palgrave Macmillan UK: 42-56. Rowlands, J. (1997). Questioning Empowerment: Working with Women in Honduras. Oxford, Oxfam. Sage, C. (2013). "The interconnected challenges for food security from a food regimes perspective: Energy, climate and malconsumption." Journal of Rural Studies 29: 71-80. Sage, C. (2014). "The transition movement and food sovereignty: From local resilience to global engagement in food system transformation." Journal of Consumer Culture 14(2): 215-236. Sbicca, J. (2012). "Growing Food Justice by Planting an Anti-Oppression Foundation: opportunities and obstacles for a budding social movement." Agriculture and Human Values 29: 455-466. Sen, A. (1981). Poverty and Famines: an essay on entitlement and deprivation. Oxford, Oxford University Press. http://www.ipes-food.org/ 23 Sen, A. (1999). Development as Freedom. Oxford, Oxford University Press. Seufort, V., N. Ramankutty and J. A. Foley (2012). "Comparing the Yields of Organic and Conventional Agriculture." Nature. Slocum, R. and K. Cadieux (2015). "Notes on the Practice of Food Justice in the U.S.: understanding and confronting trauma and inequity." Journal of Political Ecology 22: 27-52. Slocum, R., K. Cadieux and R. Blumberg (2016). "Solidarity, space, and race: toward geographies of agrifood justice." Justice Spatiale|spatial JusticE 9. Slocum, R. and A. Saldanha, Eds. (2013). Geographies of race and food fields, bodies, markets. . Aldershot, Ashgate. Smith, J. and P. Jehlicka (2013). "Quiet Sustainability: fertile lessons from Europe's Productive Gardeners." Journal of Rural Studies 32: 148-157. Stuckler, D. and M. Nestle (2012). "Big Food, Food Systems and Global Health." PLoS Med 9(6). Tarasuk, V., N. Dachner, A.-M. Hamelin, A. Ostry, P. Williams, E. Bosckei, B. Poland and K. Raine (2014). "A Survey of Food Bank Operations in Five Canadian Cities." BMC Public Health 14(1): 1234. The Trussell Trust. (2018). "End of Year Stats." Retrieved 3 July, 2018, from https://www.trusselltrust.org/news-and-blog/latest-stats/end-year-stats/#fy-2012-2013. UN Population Division (2017). World Population Prospects: the 2017 revision, key findings and advance tables. New York, Department of Economic and Social Affairs, UN. Vivero Pol, J. L. (2017). "Food as Commons or Commodity? Exploring the Links between Normative Valuations and Agency in Food Transition." Sustainability 9(442). Wekerle, G. R. (2004). "Food Justice Movements: policy, planning, and networks." Journal of Planning Educaton and Research 23: 378-386. Werkheiser, I. and S. Noll (2014). "From Food Justice to a Tool of the Status Quo: three sub-movements within local food." Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 27: 201-210. Wheeler, K. (2012). Fair Trade and the Citizen-Consumer: shopping for justice? Basingstoke, Palgrave Macmillan. Williams, J. M. and E. Holt-Giménez, Eds. (2017). Land Justice: re-imagining land, food, and the commons. Berkeley, CA, Food First Books. Woodall, P. and T. Shannon (2018). "Monopoly power corrodes choice and resiliency in the food system." The Antitrust Bulletin 63(2): 198-221. https://www.trusselltrust.org/news-and-blog/latest-stats/end-year-stats/#fy-2012-2013 work_kkc7ae7rp5cdtje3qw7oxg3jm4 ---- De-centring the psychology curriculum: Diversity, social justice, and psychological knowledge This is a repository copy of De-centring the psychology curriculum: Diversity, social justice, and psychological knowledge. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/141693/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Kontopodis, M and Jackowska, M (2019) De-centring the psychology curriculum: Diversity, social justice, and psychological knowledge. Theory and Psychology, 29 (4). pp. 506-520. ISSN 0959-3543 https://doi.org/10.1177/0959354319858419 © 2019, The Author(s). This is an author produced version of a paper published in Theory and Psychology. Uploaded in accordance with the publisher's self-archiving policy. eprints@whiterose.ac.uk https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ Reuse Items deposited in White Rose Research Online are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved unless indicated otherwise. They may be downloaded and/or printed for private study, or other acts as permitted by national copyright laws. The publisher or other rights holders may allow further reproduction and re-use of the full text version. This is indicated by the licence information on the White Rose Research Online record for the item. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing eprints@whiterose.ac.uk including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. mailto:eprints@whiterose.ac.uk https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ 1 De-centring the Psychology Curriculum: Diversity, Social Justice & Psychological Knowledge Michalis Kontopodis & Marta Jackowska self archived – pre-publication version to be published in 2019 with Theory & Psychology Abstract The psychology curriculum has close ties to the histories and cultural traditions of industrialised societies’ white middle-class populations, so it is unclear how it may reflect the interests and values of students from a variety of ethnic, racial and socio-economic backgrounds in the contemporary higher education settings. To address this question, we established an innovative research project of de-centring the psychology curriculum, so that BA students from diverse backgrounds could familiarise themselves with cultural-historical, postcolonial, feminist and other critical psychological approaches as well as reflect on the histories, contexts and epistemologies of classic developmental psychological theories and research. We conducted focus group discussions with the students as to explore their views on the introduced contents and approaches. The findings of our research form the basis for critical reflection on the possibilities and challenges of de-centring the psychology curriculum in the contemporary university settings. Introduction Since October 1974, when the American journal Teaching of Psychology was founded, long debates on psychology teaching have taken place in this as well as in similar forums such as the Studies in Higher Education, which is linked with a UK-based international academic society. Recent research has focused on a variety of topics such as: computer-based demonstrations in cognitive psychology (Copeland Scott & Houska, 2010); curriculum contents and psychology workforce readiness (Wielkiewicz & Meuwissen, 2014); online discussion forums and support with assignments (Sheen, AlJassmi & Jordan, 2017). There has been little research, however, on student views and interests with regards to the contents of the contents of the psychology curriculum. Psychology curricula have initially been developed in Global North societies and have close ties to the histories and cultural traditions of these societies’ white middle-class populations. The ethnic, racial and socio-economic characteristics of psychology students have, however, changed significantly in the past decades, and diverse groups of students are now entering higher education institutions in countries such as US, UK, Germany, Canada or Australia (Richardson, 2008; Maringe, Foskett & Woodfield, 2013; Varghese, 2013). Psychology is attracting increasing interest in the Global South, as well (Stevens & Gielen, 2007; Takooshian, Gielen, Denmark & O'Roark, 2018). The characteristics of modern psychology students beg a question on how the psychology curriculum may reflect the interests and values of students from diverse ethnic, racial and socio- economic backgrounds. Generally speaking, students from ethnic and racial minority groups and lower socio-economic backgrounds manifest significant differences from white middle-class 2 populations in subject related interests, learning styles, understandings and performance levels in higher education (Burke, 2012). While focusing specifically on psychology, Hodges and colleagues (2007) suggested that students from ethnic and racial minority groups felt loyal towards their psychology degrees; yet they simultaneously reported feelings of exclusion from, and underrepresentation in the psychology curricula. Initially the psychology curriculum (as well as psychological theories and research) reflected the cultural and historical background of white middle-class populations, which could access the relevant study and research trajectories. Psychological Societies such as the British Psychological Society have historically updated their guidelines for undergraduate and post-graduate psychology programmes as to incorporate new research areas, approaches and theoretical debates. As a result, psychology curricula in the UK currently cover qualitative as well as quantitative methodologies, discuss theoretical and historical issues in parallel to exploring neurocognition, and sometimes entail a few cross-cultural and global references – which becomes a significant selling point when marketing degrees to international students (cf. Lumby & Foskett, 2015). However, liberal and open-minded such an approach to the teaching of psychology may seem to be at a first glance, there is little reflection on the assumed impartiality and value-neutrality of most psychological knowledge. Psychology has often been criticised as the science of the “white, middle-class man” (Staeuble, 1991; Teo, 2005). It has also sometimes been racist – especially in its early phases (Richards, 2011; Lack & Abramson, 2014). In opposition to white-centred, racist psychological theory and research, Fanon published the seminal “Black skin, white masks” in the 60s (Fanon, 1952/1967), while movements to establish so-called “indigenous” or “indigenized” psychologies were taking place in the Philippines (Paredes-Canilao & Babaran-Diaz, 2013), in Taiwan (Hwang, 2005), and later on in Latin America (Kontopodis, Magalhães & Coracini, 2016), India (Sinha, 1997) and elsewhere in the world (cf. Jahoda, 2016; Brock, 2014). Various efforts to establish non-white- man-focused psychological approaches have taken place in North-Western settings, too (feminist, queer, postcolonial, etc., cf. Burman, 2005; 2017; Parker, 2015; Prilleltensky & Nelson, 2002; Walkerdine, 2001). In this frame, many scholars have argued for the necessity to “de-centre” theory and research, so that diverse polyphonic and polycentric psychologies emerge (Staeuble, 2004; Hook, 2012). Taking the aforementioned debates as a point of departure, we established an innovative research project of de-centring the psychology curriculum, so that BA students from diverse backgrounds could familiarise themselves with cultural-historical, postcolonial, feminist and other critical psychological approaches as well as reflect on the histories, contexts and epistemologies of classic developmental psychological theories and research. We aimed to investigate the students’ views on the introduced contents, and reflect, on the basis of this investigation, on how the psychology curriculum may reflect the interests and values of students from diverse ethnic, racial and socio- economic backgrounds in the contemporary higher education settings. The present article presents briefly the methodology of our study and its main findings; it concludes with a discussion on the possibilities and challenges of de-centring the psychology curriculum in the contemporary university settings while taking into account the contested history of psychology as the science of the “white, middle-class man”. Research Design & Methodology 3 Year 1 BA students from diverse ethnic, racial and socio-economic backgrounds at a South London university, have been invited to study the histories, contexts and limitations of classic developmental psychological theories in a series of lectures and seminars focusing on cultural- historical (Hedegaard, 2011; Stetsenko, 2017), postcolonial (Enriquez, 1995; Hook, 2012), feminist (Burman, 2017; Walkerdine, 2001) and other critical psychological approaches (Kontopodis, 2014; Morss, 1996). These lectures and seminars have been part of a compulsory module on psychology and human development, by the first author, which included classic approaches and references to contemporary empirical research, as well. Specifically, in five 2- hour-long lectures we explored historical, epistemological and theoretical issues in psychology and human development on the basis of the above-mentioned literature. In another five lectures, classic theories of cognitive, emotional and moral development were discussed in relation to empirical research on timely topics such as learning difficulties; new media; parenting; bullying (cf. Berk, 2013; Smith, Cowie & Blades, 2015). Lectures were attended by a cohort of about 80 students and were followed by seminars and tutorial sessions aimed at supporting students in reading and reflecting on the course literature, and at preparing for their assignment. The module was assessed by means of essay writing according to a variety of typical criteria, such as presentation and language, clarity and coherence, appropriate use of terms and critical analysis and synthesis. These contents aimed specifically at addressing the needs and interests of a diverse student population: approximately 60% of the students came from middle socio-economic and/ or White British backgrounds and 40% from lower socio- economic and/or non-white ethnic backgrounds (primarily British African-Caribbean, Asian and Arabic). Many of them were also mature students and/or parents themselves as indicated by the data collected for their registration (20% 30 years old or older, 10% 25-29 years old and 70% 18- 24 years old on average).1 Our research project focused on a small opportunity sample (n=7) of students attending the course, who reported volunteering to participate in the study for a variety of reasons including curiosity to engage with research procedures, interest in expressing their views on the course, and/or motivation to socialise with peers. Two focus groups (Bohnsack, Pfaff & Weller, 2010) in which three and four participants, respectively, took part, were conducted approximately for 1,5 hour each during the last two weeks of the course, and before grades were announced. Even though our focus group sample was small, the analysis of the participants’ grades and demographic information revealed that they could be seen as quite diverse in terms of ethnic backgrounds, age, family socio-economic circumstances, entry points and final grades. In total six out of seven participants were female; four participants were younger than 21 years, one was 23 and 2 were aged 30-35 years. Four participants were mature students and 2 had children. Three participants categorised themselves as white and the rest were of Asian or black-African/Caribbean ethnic background. In terms of parental education, two participants’ parents had no formal qualification, three had mothers but not fathers with university education, one participant’s both 1 The university name is not given as to guarantee the anonymity of participants and keep confidential relevant institutional information. The above-mentioned percentages are high when comparing to other UK Universities; they reflect the entry criteria for BA students in this particular university: The average tariff required to enter the university where the research took place was about 285 points while minimum entry standards for Cambridge are around 600 points (the highest entry level in the UK in the respective year). Out of a total of 126 universities in the UK there are about 20-25 universities with lower entry standards than that (the lowest entry standard in the UK was 220). Resource: http://www.thecompleteuniversityguide.co.uk/league-tables/rankings?o=Entry+Standards (date of access: 11-Jan-19). 4 parents had a university degree and one’s had A-levels and GCSE qualifications suggesting a broad range of parental education level amongst participants. Four participants had own or parental total income less than £20.000, and three had parental family income between 20.000-40.000 per year; which is a very low income for London living standards. In terms of essay grades two participants achieved only 40%, one participant received 58%, one 68% and there were also a 78% grade and 2=two 85% grades. One participant was diagnosed with dyslexia. In terms of entry criteria, two mature students were accepted onto the course based on their prior training and/or relevant work experience in education. Three other participants, aged 19-21 years, entered the university having obtained about 280 entry points or 320 entry points from their A levels, respectively. Two participants were international students. The questions were open with a minimal probing by the coordinator of the discussion as to minimise bias and facilitate a debate between the focus groups’ participants. Two researchers were present in the group discussions: the first author, who was the main lecturer at the developmental psychology course (white, male in his thirties) and a white (female) research assistant in her mid- twenties, who was not involved in the course and helped with the data collection. The focus group discussions were video-recorded. One more researcher (the second author) was later on involved in transcribing and analysing data, as to take a third person’s viewpoint under consideration for the interpretation. The group discussions took place in a quiet office at the university. The atmosphere was relaxed; the students laughed a lot and mostly agreed with each other. The students were seen as “experts” in the respective field and topic of investigation (Gläser & Laudel, 2004). The analysis and interpretation followed sociological approaches to knowledge and discourse (Keller, 2012; Keller, Hornidge & Schünemann, 2018) in three steps: (a) mapping of the overall structure and progression of the focus group discussion and identification of main- and sub-topics; (b) focusing on longer extracts with dense information and interpreting of what meaning is communicated and how this meaning is communicated; (c) verifying the generated categories on the whole set of data/ generalising i.e. reconstruction of implicit understandings, and discursive patterns. Particular attention was therefore paid to the choice of words as well as to the silences, interruptions and intonation. Additional materials collected included a questionnaire on the students’ personal data and family backgrounds as well as the standard course evaluation questionnaires and the student’s grades. Ethical permission to conduct this project was granted by the university authorities and all standard procedures were followed (informed consent, confidentiality, anonymity, optional participation, data safety cf. Brooks, te Riele & Maguire, 2014). The focus group discussions took place in addition to class activity outside the class time; there was no link to the class activities and any obligation or benefit for students to participate in the research. Learning about Cultural Identities is “Intriguing” The introduction of cultural-historical and postcolonial literature aroused the curiosity and interest of the students participating in the focus groups. Various students used the word “intriguing” a few times and in different moments of the group discussions as to describe their feelings about this literature, as in the example below: G2-65. D. I would say it was (…) was really quite intriguing to me it’s something 66. I’m quite interested in in terms of ahm, people living with dual, ahm cultural 67. identities (…) I was really intrigued when I saw that 5 69. this ((cultural identity)) is another layer another, ahm, aspect of child 68. development Damien2 uses the word “intriguing” here as to emphasise his genuine interest in the developmental approach to multiple cultural identities by Hedegaard (2011). Damien, refers to Hedegaard’s approach as of personal interest and relevance to him, since he himself has contact with i.e. has grown up in an area where many children have dual cultural identities: one at home and one referring to the broader area i.e. the national state they live in. He did not seem to expect, that this aspect of everyday life is included in scientific theorising on child development. While the concrete extract above refers to the specific contents, “intriguing” – as voiced by others at different times during the focus group – also referred to the students’ feeling of appreciation with the lecturers’ decision to include such literature in the course in general. The students explained that the discussed topics inspired them to engage with the relevant developmental psychological readings and theoretical models and to reflect on these while taking under consideration their personal experiences. Moreover, as the students mentioned in the focus group discussions, the readings and class activities stimulated conversations on cultural identities and multicultural education with peers outside the university. The students used words such as “relate to”, “relatable”, “engaging” in this context and seemed to agree among themselves that diversity, the development of multiple cultural identities and multicultural education are “relatable” topics of study. In the following extract another student, Horathi, argues: G2-141. H. (…) When you, when you can relate to a specific ((topic)), you know like 142. multicultural or something, I think it’s, I think it’s really 143. helpful and kind of engaging when you kind of relate to something as well. According to the students, the course’s focus on diversity motivated them to make the effort required to participate actively in the relevant class activities and to engage – before and after the lectures – with the relevant academic readings. Engaging with readings and course materials is quite challenging for students from diverse ethnic, racial and low socio-economic backgrounds in general, as they are less familiar with the academic reading and writing styles than the students from white and middle or upper socio-economic backgrounds, as we know from the relevant literature (Richardson, 2008; Burke, 2012). Addressing contents that matter for the students and reflect the challenges, which they are confronted with in their everyday lives, seems to be of particular importance, in this frame – not only in terms of student motivation but also in terms of recognition and inclusion of the diverse student voices in the psychology curriculum (cf. Boysen, 2011). Humane Approaches and Social Justice After talking about the “intriguing” and “relatable” course contents, as mentioned above, the students expressed value-related dispositions and referred to their own criteria, on the basis of which they contrast various approaches to children’s development with each other and evaluate these. Contrasting critical approaches to classic behaviourism or current neurocognitive thinking, the participating students agreed with each other that they were more interested in cultural- 2 All names are pseudonyms matching the participants’ ethnic background and gender so that the differences among the various participants are easily detectable for the readers. 6 historical, postcolonial and feminist approaches because these lead to “person-focused” i.e. “humane” professional practice, for example in school spaces: G2-427. K: I think it completely changes your approach as well. Because if, if you 428. have a teacher ((…)) from a different course, they will focus on, ok, let’s do 429. science, let’s, let’s let’s do that and that. Whereas with that knowledge, that 430. we have from here, you will approach it, you approach the person, or what 431. drives you ((…)) 432: H: Like you won’t be focused on just the curriculum, like, like I 433. said, you’ll be understanding of the actual knowledge and then executing it 434. it’ll be a lot more, I guess it’ll be a bit more, not, not fun, in a fun way, but 435. it’ll be a bit more 434. K: humane. 435. H: Yeah, a bit more adventurous and a bit more, a bit of a different manner. 436. Like you’ll see things from a different sort of (~). Both Kasia and Horathi agree in this extract that the cultural-historical approach enables teachers to approach and facilitate teaching and learning in a more “humane” or “person-” oriented, as opposed to subject-oriented manner. While Kasia used the words “drives you”, Horathi used the word “adventurous” implying that a person-cantered approach is dynamic, but that it may be more challenging and also interesting and efficient for both teachers and pupils. Another issue that was brought into the discussion and evaluation of various approaches to child development by the students was that of social justice and discrimination. Certain readings referred to examples from classroom observations in which white teachers did not fully acknowledge the challenges that pupils from different ethnic backgrounds were facing. Although our own explanations in the lectures brought to students’ attention various perspectives and challenges teachers may have been facing, the participating ethnic minority students seemed to identify themselves with the ethnic minority pupils in these examples, rather than with the teachers. The students expressed much concern that pupils may be treated unfairly because of their colour, race, origin or ethnicity. Therefore, they agreed that critical and culturally sensitive psychological approaches are necessary to develop best practice in teaching and childcare institutions. The extract presented below is exemplary for this kind of talk: G1-228. B: yeah, me and Raha were discussing about with another friend as well, 229. and hmm it was it was unfair on them (…) I think like any if you reflect on 230. how it is now (…) you can see how hmm (…) some people do get treated 231. unfairly because of where (…) they’ve come from and, the back ((…)) 232. and like just because they come from another country and some people 233. don’t. I know it isn’t an issue now ‘cause you hear on the news and stuff 234. (…) but like the text it was really unfair on them because the teachers 235. didn’t treat them equally (…), and you know in (…) education in general 236. the policy is that they always say that everyone should be treated fairly 237. and equally and no one should be discriminated or anything like that, so 238. for me to see that in the text it was just like, that’s was just like that’s quite 239. sad like why would them have do that that’s not really nice. Discussing value-related issues openly occurred quite intuitively since the readings and discussed materials offered the ground for such a debate to take place. Beverley expresses here her concern that pupils may be treated unfairly in school because of their country of origin. Through repeating 7 words like “unfair on them”, “really unfair”, “equally”, “discrimination”, “not really nice” she takes a clear position on the side of the pupils who may have been discriminated, and emphasises that none should be discriminated in education and in society, in general, which was a shared concern among the other students, too. Psychological Knowledge and Epistemological Concerns Psychology has not only been the science created by and studied primarily by the “white, middle- class man”; it has also been one of the main disciplines that enabled that “white, middle-class man” to help “Others” to “develop” – the “Others” being from diverse ethnic, racial and socio-economic backgrounds (Teo, 2005; Mills, 2014). “Knowledge production” and “development” have not taken place, however, on neutral grounds, but within a continuing global history of discrimination, racism, wars, and exploitation of various local populations (Mignolo, 2012; Kontopodis, 2014); The science of psychology and – more broadly speaking – the university, as an institution, have unfortunately, often being an intrinsic part of this contested history (cf. Howell, & Tuitt, 2003; Richards, 2011; Parker, 2015; Wilder, 2013). The “Others” may nowadays study psychology themselves, and then work as psychology practitioners in their own local communities and places of origin, instead of the communities relying on the psychological services provided by white, middle-class psychologists; this shift does not unfortunately, however, imply straightforward shifts in the historically rooted unequal distribution of power (cf. Hook, 2007). In our focus groups, we were quite perplexed to realise that, even if the students reflected explicitly and critically on value-related issues and social justice with regards to psychological theory and practice, as referred to above; this reflection was part of a broader endeavour though to identify the “best” developmental psychological knowledge that would enable the “perfect” practice for the “benefit” of all children: G2-551. D: I just think some, some knowledge of developmental psychology ahm could make 552. a difference to so many people, if they knew, if they just knew the effects of so 553. many things that are [going] 554. H: [oh yeah] 555. D: around their children, [around themselves] 556. K: [it’s power it’s a] power 557. D: (…) around their teenagers, yeah, it’s amazing ((…)) 573. D: Well yeah what you’ re saying there is no handbook for being a good parent. You 574: know, there are norms, to every society and every culture, but there is no 575: handbook that says do this and do that and you’ll be able to be a perfect parent. 576: (…) however if you have someone with knowledge of developmental 577. K: you’ll 578. D: have perfect child psycho[logy] 579. H: [you’ll] understand which factors 580. D: regardless of your culture (...) regardless [of your] 581. K: [What could] harm, (…) what [could], 582. H: [yeah] 583. D: gender. Yeah, you could have a rough idea of how, of what to do best by the child 584. H: or to benefit, what would be beneficial for it In this example, echoing each other, the three students agree that developmental psychological knowledge could be beneficial for any child regardless of the child’s culture or gender. In 8 accordance with widespread popular understandings, the students express a strong belief in psychology as a system of knowledge that is objective and impartial – even universal – and aims at benefiting all children – a discourse, which, as already explained, has been much debated in the relevant critical psychological literature. Questioning the discourse that psychological knowledge is “objective” and “universal” proved to be more difficult for the BA students than we had anticipated; The students, as a matter of fact, had spent a significant amount of money and resources to study psychology, hoping to obtain “objective” knowledge and “help” their families and communities after their graduation. Psychology graduates from diverse ethnic, racial and socio-economic backgrounds may, in such a frame, reproduce rather uncritically the so-called paternalist approach i.e. seek affirmation of superiority through the provision of help in their professional roles, and practices instead of raising awareness of the complex structures, viewpoints, and power relations that create and maintain exploitation and inequality (cf. Stein & Andreotti, 2016). The question poses itself here – echoing Brock (2006) – whether a “de-colonial”, “postcolonial”, “feminist” or “indigenous” “psychology” “curriculum” is possible at all, or whether these word combinations are oxymora and no de- centered psychology curriculum can ever exist. It would be far stretching for us to adopt such a position without further investigation; we suggest though that lecturers and students should continuously reflect on the power relations that have historically shaped the production of psychological knowledge, and be aware, in this frame, of the inherent difficulties entailed in challenging prevailing understandings of the nature and function of psychological knowledge. Discussion and Conclusions: De-centring the Psychology Curriculum The psychology curriculum has close ties to the histories and cultural traditions of industrialised societies’ white middle-class populations. Psychology students are no longer, however, a homogenous group largely consisting of white, middle-class men. It is timely and worthy, in this frame, to bring a variety of critical psychological readings for debate into university lecture theatres and seminar rooms, and to discuss the foundations, histories and potential limitations of psychological knowledge with diverse students. The present article explored how the contents of the psychology curriculum can reflect the interests and values of students from diverse ethnic, racial and socio-economic backgrounds. While taking critical distance from psychology as the science of the “white, middle-class man” (cf. Hook, 2012; Teo, 2005), we established an innovative research project of de-centring the psychology curriculum, so that BA students from diverse backgrounds could familiarise themselves with polyphonic and polycentric psychologies (Staeuble, 2004). By analysing focus group discussions with the students, we explored their views on the introduced contents and approaches. The scale of our research has obviously been limited; follow-up studies with larger samples and repeated focus groups over longer periods of time could explore potential differences, in terms of ethnic, racial and socio-economic backgrounds and gender, in the discursive positioning among various students as well as document potential changes in their views and understandings over time. According to the analysis of the focus group discussions, students were “intrigued” by cultural- historical, feminist, postcolonial and other critical psychology approaches, as these approaches address issues which the students encounter in their everyday lives in – often marginalised – ethnic communities. The students expressed concerns with regards to diversity, multicultural education and social justice in relation to psychological theory and professional practice, and brought to the 9 foreground their own everyday experiences when doing that. At the same time, it proved difficult for the students to question the discourse that psychology is a system of objective, impartial and even universal knowledge that aims at benefiting all – a discourse, which has been much debated in the relevant critical psychological literature. On the basis of these findings and echoing current research and debates on de-colonising higher education (Stein & Andreotti, 2016), we propose that the psychology curriculum should not only enable students to access to culturally enriched psychology handbooks and teaching materials; it should also enourage continuous critical reflection on the values and epistemological dispositions entailed in psychological theory and research. This is a difficult task though: relevant theory and research in the field of “indigenous psychologies” (Brock, 2014) as well as in the fields of “postcolonial” and “de-colonial studies” caution that particular forms of knowledge and certain modes of life have been privileged over others in the course of modernisation. In this context, a wide range of people around the globe has often not even been able to communicate their views and participate into the relevant institutional spaces (cf. Spivak, 2012; Mills, 2014). Even if there is no straightforward way to address this issue, it is important that psychology faculty reflects on the fact that psychological knowledge production and dissemination has not taken place on neutral grounds, but within a continuing global history of racism, inequality and asymmetrical relations of power between children and adults (Parker, 2015; Prilleltensky & Nelson, 2002). Following from such a critical stance, psychology faculty may undertake a few concrete steps as to address the challenges in dialogue with their diverse students. These steps would be:  Creating spaces for psychology students from diverse ethnic, racial and socio-economic backgrounds and age groups to explore their own questions;  Discussing epistemological and value-related issues openly with students from diverse ethnic, racial and socio-economic backgrounds, who bring with them their own interests, forms of knowledge and value-related positions, as well as their own community histories and future imaginaries;  Empowering students to search for and critically analyse differentiated readings and sources of information in their own languages on topics of their own interests. Student engagement could be facilitated through self-organised student seminars and study groups, as well as through alternative assessment formats such as student presentations or small-scale research projects. Of course, this would also require appropriate resources, such as time for discussions with student representatives and engagement with diversified readings for the involved academics; engagement within professional accredited organisations, such as the British Psychological Society, as well as support with programme development and evaluation procedures. On the longer run, participatory and co-productive research with the students and graduates from diverse ethnic, racial and socio-economic backgrounds themselves (Campbell & Vanderhoven, 2016) would be necessary for a variety of topics, which are relevant for these students and their communities, to be investigated across diverse settings so that new teaching materials are developed. Whether such a de-centred psychology curriculum could emerge from the highly contested history of psychology as a discipline remains to be seen. We leave this question open and look forward to the answer, which future developments in widening participation in higher education may stipulate. 10 Acknowledgements We would like to thank Christine Becker-Hardt for her kind contribution in the early stages of this research. A special thanks is also due to the students who participated in our research project. References Berk, L. E. (2013). Child development. Boston: Pearson. Bohnsack, R., Pfaff, N., & Weller, W. (Eds.). (2010). Qualitative analysis and documentary method in international educational research. Opladen: Barbara Budrich. Boysen, G. A. (2011). Diversity topics covered in teaching of psychology courses. Teaching of Psychology, 38(2), 89-93. Brock, A. C. (2006). Introduction. In A. C. Brock (Ed.), Internationalizing the history of psychology (pp. 1–15). New York: New York University Press. Brock, A. (2014). Indigenous psychologies. In Teo, T., Encyclopedia of critical psychology, (4), (pp. 949-955). Boston, MA: Springer. Brooks R., te Riele K. & Maguire, M. (2014). Ethics and education research. London: Sage. Burke, P. J. (2012). The right to higher education: Beyond widening participation. London: Routledge. Burman, E. (2005). Engendering culture in psychology. Theory & Psychology, 15(4), 527-548. Burman, E. (2017). Deconstructing developmental psychology. London and New York: Routledge. Campbell, H. & Vanderhoven, D. (2016). Knowledge that matters: Realising the potential of co- production. Manchester: N8/ESRC. Copeland, D. E., Scott, J. R., & Houska, J. A. (2010). Computer-based demonstrations in cognitive psychology: Benefits and costs. Teaching of Psychology, 37(2), 141-145. Edwards, J.A. & Lampert, M.D. (1993). Talking data: Transcription and coding in discourse research. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Enriquez, V. (1995). From colonial to liberation psychology. Manila, Philippines: De La Salle University Press. Fanon, F. (1952/1967). Black skin, white masks. New York: Groove Press Inc. Gläser, J. & Laudel, G. (2004). Experteninterviews und qualitative Inhaltsanalyse als Instrumente rekonstruierender Untersuchungen. Wiesbaden: Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften. Hedegaard, M. (2011). A cultural-historical approach to children’s development of multiple cultural identities. In M. Kontopodis, C. Wulf, & B. Fichtner (Eds.), Children, development and education: Cultural, historical, anthropological perspectives (pp. 117- 136). Dordrecht, London, New Delhi and New York: Springer. Hook, D. (2007). Foucault, psychology & the analytics of power. New York: Palgrave- Macmillan. Hook D. (2012). A critical psychology of the postcolonial: The mind of Apartheid. Hove, UK: Routledge. Hodges, I., Jobanaputra, S., Pearson, C., Reed, C. & Smith, S. (2007). Mapping exclusion in undergraduate psychology: Towards a common architecture of the minority student experience. Final report for the Higher Education Academy Psychology Network 11 Department Teaching Enhancement Scheme. Available at: https://www.heacademy.ac.uk/node/3947 (date of access: 18-July-2018). Howell, A., & Tuitt, F. (2003). Race and higher education: Rethinking pedagogy in diverse college classrooms. Cambridge: Harvard Educational Review Reprint Series. Hwang, K.-K. (2005). From anti-colonialism to postcolonialism: The emergence of Chinese indigenous psychology in Taiwan. International Journal of Psychology, 40(4), 228-238. Jahoda, G. (2016). On the rise and decline of ‘indigenous psychology’. Culture & Psychology, 22(2), 169-181. Keller, R. (2012). Doing discourse research. London: Sage. Keller, R., Hornidge, A.-K., & Schünemann, W. J. (Eds.). (2018). The sociology of knowledge approach to discourse: Investigating the politics of knowledge and meaning-making. London: Routledge. Kontopodis, M. (2014). Neoliberalism, pedagogy & human development. London & New York: Routledge. Kontopodis, M., Magalhães, M. C., & Coracini, M. J. (Eds.). (2016). Facing poverty and marginalization: 50 years of critical research in Brazil. Bern, Oxford and New York: Peter Lang. Kim, U., Yang, K. S., & Hwang, K. K. (Eds) (2006). Indigenous and cultural psychology: People in context. New York: Springer. Lack, C. W., & Abramson, C. (Eds.). (2014). Psychology gone astray: A selection of racist & sexist literature from early psychological research. Oklahoma: Onus Books. Lumby, J., & Foskett, N. (2015). Internationalization and culture in higher education. Educational Management Administration & Leadership, 44(1), 95-111. Maringe F, Foskett N, Woodfield, S. (2013). Emerging internationalisation models in an uneven global terrain: findings from a global survey. Compare: A Journal of Comparative and International Education, 43(1), 9-36. Mignolo, W. (2012). Local histories/ Global designs: Coloniality, subaltern knowledges, and border thinking. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Mills, C. (2014). Decolonizing global mental health: The psychiatrization of the majority world. London and New York: Routledge. Morss, J. (1996). Growing critical: Alternatives to developmental psychology. London: Routledge. Paredes-Canilao, N., & Babaran-Diaz, M. A. (2013). Sikolohiyang Pilipino: 50 years of critical- emancipatory social science in the Philippines. Annual Review of Critical Psychology, 10, 765-783. Parker, I. (2015). Handbook of critical psychology. London and New York: Routledge. Prilleltensky, I. & Nelson, G. (2002). Doing psychology critically: Making a difference in diverse settings. New York: Palgrave-Macmillan. Richards, G. (2011). Race, racism and psychology: Towards a reflexive history. London: Routledge. Richardson, J.T. (2008). The attainment of ethnic minority students in UK higher education. Studies in Higher Education, 33(1), 33-48. Sheen, M., AlJassmi, M. A., & Jordan, T. R. (2017). Teaching About Psychological Disorders: A Case for Using Discussion Boards in the Classroom. Teaching of Psychology, 44(1), 74-77. Sinha, D. (1997). Indigenizing psychology. In J. W. Berry, Y. H. Pooringa, & J. Pandey (Eds.), Handbook of cross-cultural psychology Vol. 1 (pp. 129-169). Boston, MA: Allyn & Bacon. Smith, P.; Cowie, H. & Blades, M. (2015). Understanding children’s development. Chichester: Wiley. https://www.heacademy.ac.uk/node/3947 12 Spivak, G. C. (2012). An aesthetic education in the era of globalization. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Stein, S. & Andreotti, V. (2016). Decolonization and higher education. In M. Peters (Ed.), Encyclopaedia of educational philosophy and theory (pp. 1-6). Singapore: Springer. Staeuble, I. (1991). Psychological man and human subjectivity in historical perspective. History of the Human Sciences, 4(3), 417-432. Staeuble, I. (2004). De-centering Western perspectives: Psychology and the disciplinary order in the First and Third World. In A.C. Brock, J. Louw, W. van Hoorn (Eds.), Rediscovering the History of Psychology (pp. 183-205). Boston, MA: Springer. Stevens, M., & Gielen, U. P. (Eds.). (2007). Toward a global psychology: Theory, research, intervention, and pedagogy. Mahwah, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum. Stetsenko, A. (2017). The transformative mind: Expanding Vygotsky’s approach to development and education. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press. Takooshian, H, Gielen, U.P., Denmark, F.L., & O'Roark, A.M. (Eds.). (2018). Visions and resources for international psychology: 75 years of the International Council of Psychologists. New York, NY: Global Scholarly Publications. Teo, T. (2005). The critique of psychology: From Kant to postcolonial theory. New York: Springer. Varghese, N. V. (2013). Globalization and higher education: Changing trends in cross border education. Analytical Reports in International Education, 5(1), 7-20. Walkerdine, V., Lucey, H., & Melody, J. (2001). Growing up girl: psychosocial explorations of gender and class. New York: New York University Press. Wielkiewicz, R. M., & Meuwissen, A. S. (2014). A lifelong learning scale for research and evaluation of teaching and curricular effectiveness. Teaching of Psychology, 41(3), 220- 227. Wilder, C. S. (2013). Ebony and ivy: Race, slavery, and the troubled history of America’s universities. New York: Bloomsbury Publishing. Appendix Transcription symbols (adapted from: Edwards & Lampert, 1993) G1/G2 Focus Group 1/ Focus Group 2 [text] text articulated simultaneously by the interviewer and interviewee (…) pause lasting less than 1 second (~) unclear word ((…)) text omissions or explanations added by the researchers work_kldxsrycgbhfzjpkw6wh2c6qfq ---- Environmental Justice through Improved Efficiency Environmental Justice through Improved Efficiency Peter S. Wenz University of Illinois at Springfield Introduction Environmental philosophers in western democracies often attempt to influence public policies. We advocate, for example, habitat protection for endangered species, sustainable agriculture, and increased use of renewable sources of energy. But how do we convince fellow citizens? We must relate our proposals to commonly held values. In this paper I enlist the commonly held values of efficiency, justice, and environmental justice in support of environmentalist proposals for more public and mass transportation, particularly for transportation by rail. My argument goes beyond what Bryan Norton calls the convergence thesis,[1] insofar as anthropocentric values support environmentalist proposals regarding transportation without considering the welfare of future generations of human beings. Efficiency is widely considered praiseworthy in our culture. However, I do not claim it is our most important value, or that it alone supports environmentalism. Efficiency is highlighted here due to its usual association with environmentally ruinous "progress." Making efficiency an environmentalist value removes a major ideological impediment to environmental sanity. PART I: JUSTICE, ENVIRONMENTAL JUSTICE, AND EFFICIENCY Justice and Environmental Justice Justice and Environmental Justice I do not attempt here a full characterization of either justice or environmental justice, which are topics that I have considered elsewhere.[2] For present purposes it suffices to note that justice generally increases when the burdens of meeting basic needs, and the benefits derived from social and economic life, are more equal, except where moral considerations and other values support greater inequality. In other words, equality is presumptively just, but the presumption can be rebutted. Environmental justice is merely justice as applied to policies and programs related to the quality of the environment. Anti-environmental Invocations of Efficiency A common view that pits efficiency against the environment (a view that I oppose in this paper), starts with the claim that human wants are insatiable. This creates scarcity. According to environmental economist Clement A. Tisdell, economic activity aims to reduce scarcity. "The basic [economic] problem is considered to be how to manage or administer resources so as to minimize scarcity, that is, the 'gap' between individuals' demand for commodities and the available supply of them."[3] Efficiency is necessary because the more efficiently people use resources, the more human needs and wants can be satisfied. Free markets are commonly thought to promote efficiency. Ideally, suppliers of goods and services compete for customers' money by offering better products at lower prices. Prices are kept low by using raw materials and labor efficiently. Many people claim, for example, that farmers can gain greater yields at lower cost by growing cash crops on their fields year after year. People who accept this view of agricultural efficiency recommend that farmers apply artificial, nitrogen fertilizers every year to maintain soil fertility, which is otherwise degraded by continuous cash cropping. "Efficient" farmers reduce labor costs by using chemical herbicides, rather than human labor, to control weeds. They save additionally on labor when they use large farm machinery to plant seeds, spread fertilizers and herbicides, and harvest crops from large fields where such machinery is most useful. Such farmers are widely regarded the most efficient in the world. Food is relatively inexpensive so people who farm this way compete successfully in the free market. Because the food is cheap, consumers have money left over to buy other items that they want and need. Free market, agricultural competition seems, then, to ameliorate scarcity. However, most environmentalists oppose this kind of agriculture. They oppose the use of artificial fertilizers because these are made from petrochemicals, a non-renewable resource. Processing the chemicals pollutes water and air. Chemical herbicides also add to water pollution. What is more, only crop rotation maintains soil fertility in the long run. The large fields required by large farm equipment deprive non-agricultural species, such as birds and rodents, the habitat that traditionally exists in hedgerows surrounding smaller fields. It would seem, then, that environmentalists are opposed to modern agricultural efficiency and the reduction of scarcity. Free market, efficient agriculture seems opposed to equality as well. As some farmers prosper through the use of expensive, modern methods, others lose their farms because they lack the capital or the vision to modernize. Advocates of free market-induced efficiency do not consider such inequality unjust if it is necessary to reduce scarcity. I argue that real efficiency is opposed neither to environmental concerns nor to greater equality. I illustrate this thesis through extended consideration of transportation. But I must first clarify the meaning of "efficiency," and do so by continuing a more cursory consideration of agriculture. What "Efficiency" Means Efficiency refers primarily to a relationship of inputs to outputs. Other things being equal, efficiency increases as valued inputs in limited supply decrease, and valued outputs increase. Most often the relevant inputs and outputs are implicit in claims of efficiency, because they are part of people's background understanding. For example, agriculture in the United States is often said to be the most efficient in the world. The understood inputs are labor hours expended directly on agriculture and the outputs are bushels of grain. However, sometimes the understood inputs are not the only ones worth considering. The input in agriculture could be arable land, so that efficiency would be measured in output per hectare. Or the input could be money invested, making efficiency a measure of output per dollar invested. The output could also be altered from bushels of grain to nutrition available for people, or to monetary returns. If both input and output are put in purely monetary terms, the efficiency calculation amounts to a standard calculation of return on investment. If, however, the input is monetary and the output is nutrition available for human beings, then a different agricultural strategy may be deemed most efficient, because feeding poor, starving people may not be the way to gain the greatest monetary return on investment. Because many different efficiency calculations are possible, judgments that environmentalism opposes (or favors) efficiency cannot be made in abstraction from either a given type of endeavor (agriculture in this example), or determination of inputs and outputs appropriate to that endeavor. How do we recognize the most appropriate inputs and outputs? The most appropriate inputs are those that are necessary and in short supply. The most appropriate outputs are those that correspond to the legitimate goal(s) of the enterprise. Again, consider agriculture. Atmospheric nitrogen is valuable and necessary for agriculture, but because it is so plentiful, reasonable calculations of agricultural efficiency do not rate farming practices according to their conservation of such nitrogen. Worldwide, the same can be said of labor hours expended directly on agriculture. Unemployment is a major problem in many parts of the world. An abundance of labor makes calculations of agricultural efficiency according to labor hours expended directly on agriculture about as reasonable as calculations based on the use of atmospheric nitrogen. In agriculture, the most appropriate inputs are arable land, fertile soil, and fresh water. They are necessary, and the currently short supply is diminishing quickly. Worldwatch's Gary Gardner reports that arable land is being lost at an alarming rate to urban expansion,[4] and that much soil fertility is being lost to salination[5] and topsoil erosion.[6] Water shortages affect many parts of the world already, and are expected to become acute in many other parts, including the United States, in the next century.[7] So reasonable calculations of efficiency in agriculture will prominently feature arable land, fertile soil, and fresh water among inputs to be conserved. And what is the most appropriate output? Rather than bushels of grain, it would be people fed adequately or well, as feeding people has always been the main goal of agriculture. When agricultural efficiency is understood as the efficient use of arable land, fertile soil, and fresh water to feed people, conflict between environmentalist concerns and efficiency disappears. It is beyond the scope of the present paper to argue the case in detail here, but the outline of the argument is that the highly mechanized, high-input agriculture that environmentalists oppose makes inefficient use of scarce resources needed to feed people. It tends to degrade soils and waste water. The major output is grain that is fed to animals that are grown for their meat. This is inefficient because the animals use about 90% of the food value of the grain for their own bodies' maintenance, leaving only 10% to feed people. Thus, environmentalist critiques of modern factory farming do not call for reduced efficiency, but for increased efficiency in the effort to ameliorate scarcity. This is the kind of argument that I make below, and in greater detail, concerning transportation. Efficiency and Plural Values This analysis of the concept of efficiency implies that judgments of efficiency cannot be divorced from judgments of value, and that plural values may need to be considered. In the case of agriculture, for example, the values of arable land, fresh water, and fertile soil all had to be considered. Discomfort with the need to make controversial value judgments motivates some thinkers to seek a single measure of value that can be used on all occasions and for all endeavors. The most influential proposal of this kind comes from economists who have tried to reduce all values to a medium of exchange, such as money. On this view, the relevant "valued input" into any activity is monetary investment (money and the monetary worth of all non-monetary inputs), and the "valued output" is profit (gross income minus expenses). Society as a whole is thought to be operating most efficiently when its resources (the monetary value of all its inputs) are used to maximize gross domestic product (GDP) (the monetary worth of its outputs). Some consequences of measuring efficiency by GDP alone suffice to show the inappropriateness of reducing all inputs and outputs to monetary terms. The most abstract consideration was put forward in 1819 by classical economist Lauderdale, who made a distinction between "public wealth" and "private riches." Both public wealth and private riches contain what "man desires as useful or delightful to him," but private riches, unlike public wealth, have exchange value because they exist "in a degree of scarcity."[8] The GDP, of course, measures everything in terms of exchange values. Because exchange values increase with scarcity, there is a paradox: "Private riches could expand while public wealth declined simply because formerly abundant objects with great use value but no exchange value became scarce, and thereby acquired exchange value and were henceforth counted as riches."[9] Lauderdale maintained that "the common sense of mankind would revolt at a proposal for augmenting wealth by creating a scarcity of any good generally useful and necessary to man."[10] To recognize how revolting this is, consider home security. In a society where there is little crime, people can feel, and be, secure in their homes without elaborate home security systems. In such a society home security is part of public wealth. Imagine that social disaffection increases, or the effectiveness of law enforcement decreases, and home security becomes a problem. People now buy elaborate home security systems and purchase the services of private security personnel, because home security is now a scarce item. It has become part of what Lauderdale called "private riches." Because more goods and services are bought and sold, the GDP increases, all other things being equal. So if GDP were the sole measure of efficiency in society, a society where people are insecure in their homes is more efficient than one where they enjoy home security without expense. This is absurd.[11] Other absurdities abound, because increases in GDP often fail to improve people's welfare. Some increases in GDP simply compensate for the loss of welfare. For example, WorldWatch's Sandra Postel reports that cleanup expenditures after the Alaskan oil spill of 1989 added $2 billion to the economy, and air pollution in the United States causes illnesses whose medical treatment costs $40 billion annually.[12] Again, it is absurd to suppose that society is doing better when it has pollution to clean up and related illnesses to cure. Of course, some workers and investors benefit when people spend money on private security systems, environmental clean-up and medical care. But a more secure, pollution-free and healthy society could use its resources to further improve welfare, rather than merely compensate for welfare losses. This is surely better, all things considered, even if the GDP is somewhat lower. If GDP is unacceptable as the sole measure of economic efficiency in society, then, because no other sole measure is plausible, judgments of efficiency will have to be made using a plurality of values. This means that we will have to say, as I have illustrated above in the case of American agriculture, that a given practice may be efficient on one measure, but not so efficient on another. In such cases purely mathematical calculations will not suffice to judge efficiency. Instead, we will have to use common sense (i.e. the common web of value beliefs that we have internalized through socialization) to determine which practices and strategies are, all things considered, more efficient than others. PART II: TRANSPORTATION I now argue that, all things considered, transportation policies favored by environmentalists, such as greater reliance on public and mass transit systems, and greater use of railroads, are not only better environmentally than current emphases on automotive transport, but are also more efficient and just. Current Problems Most of the current transportation problems in the United States stem from excessive reliance on automobiles and trucks to transport people and goods. Traffic congestion "not only causes stress and inconvenience," writes WorldWatch researcher Marcia Lowe, but also costs countries billions of dollars a year in lost employee time and delayed delivery of goods. The United States General Accounting Office (GAO) reports that productivity losses from highway congestion cost the nation some $100 billion annually.[13] The Texas Traffic Institute estimates that, in 1988, traffic congestion in U.S. urban areas cost more than $400 per vehicle. In cities in the Northeast, the figure rose to $750 per vehicle.[14] The Union of Concerned Scientists' Deborah Gordon reports similar findings: The Federal Highway Administration (FHWA) estimates that congestion wastes 1.4 billion gallons of fuel annually, 2 percent of the energy currently used for highway passenger transport, and the U.S. Department of Transportation estimates that congestion costs each driver $375 annually in extra fuel and maintenance expenses.[15] What is more, the problem seems to be getting worse. Gordon writes, "According to an FHWA estimate, in just three years, between 1985 and 1988, traffic delays from road congestion increased by 57 percent."[16] The future looks bleak. "The U.S. General Accounting Office has calculated that if present trends continue, road congestion in the United States will triple in only 15 years even if capacity is increased by 20 percent, a goal that is unlikely to be achieved."[17] The result could be a 10-fold increase in urban rush-hour congestion. What these figures mean is that by 2005 the average commuter from one suburb of a metropolitan area to another suburb could spend up to five times as long in traffic as in 1990. This could mean moving at five miles per hour over a 10-mile trip - a two-hour commute. Not only time but fuel would be wasted; the FHWA projects that by 2005, 7.3 billion gallons of fuel will be wasted each year - 7 percent of projected oil use for highway passenger transport.[18] Automobile Accidents are another problem. Traffic injuries and fatalities cost society roughly thirty cents per gallon of gas used in automotive transportation.[19] These financial losses and, more importantly, related human tragedies, could be reduced dramatically by a switch to rail. "In the United States, the risk of death in an auto accident is roughly 18 times that for rail...."[20] Air pollution caused by automotive transport takes a larger toll on people's health, and costs even more money. According to Deborah Gordon, "The annual cost to human health and the environment from vehicle pollution has been estimated at between $4 and $93 billion. In addition to morbidity, as many as 120,000 deaths each year can be linked to air pollution."[21] These problems could be ameliorated significantly through greater reliance on mass transit. "Cars and light trucks have the highest emission levels per passenger mile for all principal pollutants. In fact, a single-occupancy car emits twice as much NOx, three times as much CO2, 10 times as much hydrocarbon, and 17 times as much CO as mass transit."[22] Vehicle air pollution damages more than people's health. It "is also responsible for extensive environmental deterioration, including damage to agriculture and wildlife, corrosion and soiling of buildings, [and] degradation of visibility....[23] Military security in the United States is aggravated by reliance on automotive transport, because such transport uses more oil than the U.S. can produce domestically. By 2000, the average barrel of crude will be 40 percent domestic and 60 percent imported.... More troubling in terms of national security, the U.S. is importing an increasing amount of oil from politically unstable sources, including the Persian Gulf countries and Nigeria.... These countries accounted for one-third of all U.S. imports in 1989 - up 11 percent from a year earlier.[24] The military buildup in 1991 to protect oil from the Persian Gulf "cost the equivalent of an average 40 cents per gallon of imported gasoline.... Furthermore, the cost will be a continuing one, since even if future wars are avoided, the U.S. is expected to maintain a constant military presence in the Middle East."[25] The U.S. trade deficit with the rest of the world is worsened by reliance on foreign oil. "According to Department of Commerce calculations, imported oil accounted for 50 percent of the nation's $108-billion trade deficit in 1990."[26] There are other problems associated with over reliance on cars and trucks to transport people and goods, but the above suffice to make the point. I add here only that these problems sometimes interact to create negative synergy. For example, congestion exacerbates problems of air pollution. "Carbon dioxide emissions double when average speed drops from 30 to 10 mph, and hydrocarbon and carbon monoxide emissions triple at speeds of less than 35 mph compared with a constant speed of 55 mph." This takes a double toll on human health. First, more pollutants that impair health are emitted per mile driven. Second, more people spend more time in the vicinity of the greatest concentration of pollution when they are stuck in traffic jams. "Exposure to ozone can cause chest tightness, coughing, headaches, and nausea as well as pulmonary disease, heart disease, and cancer."[27] Traffic congestion and related increases in exposure to air pollution can also precipitate traffic accidents. High carbon monoxide concentrations on crowded roads, for example, can restrict oxygen flow to the brain of a driver sitting in traffic, impairing driving performance.... Aggressive behavior and physiological reactions have also been linked to exposure to congested traffic conditions.[28] Besides taking a toll on human health, increased accident rates trigger higher insurance premiums. More Efficient Alternatives Transport by rail is the key to a more efficient transportation system. Consider, for example, the problems of energy dependence and air pollution. According to Marcia Lowe, For every kilometer of travel, an intercity passenger train consumes only one- third as much energy per rider as a commercial airplane, and one-sixth as much as a car carrying only the driver. Commuters who take light rail or the subway to work instead of driving solo slash their contribution to urban smog, cutting nitrogen oxide emissions from each trip by 60 percent and nearly eliminating carbon monoxide and particulate emissions.[29] An increased use of rail would also relieve traffic congestion, and, as noted above, reduce significantly injuries and deaths due to transportation accidents. Rail makes more efficient use of space. "Two railroad tracks can carry as many people in an hour as 16 lanes of highway."[30] Efficient use of space is particularly important in crowded urban areas where land values are high. In addition, "rather than the strip malls and sprawling developments that spring up along highways..., urban rail typically encourages compact, higher-value land use."[31] More compact development lessens transportation difficulties because people typically are closer to where they need to go, so they can walk or ride a bicycle. This benefits their health and further relieves traffic congestion, air pollution, and energy dependence. Compact development that results from using rail can improve prospects for economic growth. Montgomery County, Maryland - a county of 740,000 people near Washington, D.C. - is a case in point. A long-range planning study for the county found that if urban growth continued in the usual auto- and highway- oriented pattern - even at a slower pace - the resulting traffic congestion would stifle further economic development. In contrast, focusing most new urban growth in pedestrian- and bicycle-friendly clusters along an expanded rail and bus system - and revising commuter subsidies to discourage the use of cars - would enable the county to double its current number of jobs and households without exacerbating traffic congestion.[32] Intercity rail tends to help keep city centers vital, because most train stations in large cities are downtown. This encourages compact development that lessens distances to be traveled and fosters walking and the use public transportation. Public sector investment in public transport is more efficient than investment in improved infrastructure for automobiles. A recent U.S. study looked at the impact of government transport expenditures on worker productivity. A 10-year, $100 billion increase in public transport spending was estimated to boost worker output by $521 billion - compared with $237 billion for the same level of spending on highways. Moreover, public transport investments began returning net benefits nearly three times as quickly as highway expenditures.[33] A 1991 study of transportation investment alternatives in Philadelphia reached similar conclusions. The study compared the economic effects of investing in rehabilitation and continued operation of SEPTA (the light rail, subway, and commuter rail system in the Philadelphia metropolitan area) with cutting or eliminating its services. The study found that for every dollar of public spending on rebuilding and operating SEPTA, $3 would accrue to the state and the region as a direct result of improved transport. The total economic impact... would be nine dollars for every dollar invested.[34] The European Conference of Ministers of transport found similarly that the total social benefits of investment for intercity travel in fast trains (the TGV), was two-thirds greater than investment in highways.[35] Transporting freight by rail is also more efficient than highway (truck) transport. "Although they carry only 20 percent of the nation's payload, trucks burn 59 percent of the energy devoted to moving freight."[36] Rail, by contrast, "although it moves one-third of U.S. freight, accounts for a scant 5 percent of energy consumption."[37] In addition, "because trains can use cleaner and more diversified fuel sources than trucks, such as electricity, shifting freight from trucks to trains would reduce both emissions and U.S. demand for imported oil. Moreover, greater use of trains would reduce highway congestion and traffic accidents."[38] Inefficiency through Subsidies Most people in the United States imagine that automobile transport is cheaper for them than public transportation, and that lower prices reflect efficiency. Public transportation, they have been told, requires considerable government subsidies. These people do not realize that cars are highly subsidized. With much less subsidy, public transportation could be convenient and widely available. Many car subsidies are hidden and long-standing. Consider, for example, subsidies for parking. Deborah Gordon points out: Recent studies have found that 75 percent of all commuters park in free, employer-provided spaces; an additional 18 percent park for free in on-street spaces.... Studies conclude that "free" parking costs employers $166-$1,657 per space per year (in 1985 dollars). Parking is expensive: an above-grade space can cost up to $18,000 to build, and underground parking is at least twice that much. Moreover, a 500-car parking lot requires an estimated 170,000 gallons of gasoline to construct and 1,200 gallons of gasoline for annual maintenance. Parking has hidden costs as well. Land devoted to parking means lost revenues from the tax-generating activities it precludes - residential, commercial, and industrial.[39] In large measure, "free" parking is subsidized by the customers of the employers who provide such parking. This is, in effect, a hidden subsidy of automotive transport by the consuming public. When the employer is a unit of government, the consumer subsidizes automobile use through tax contributions. Even when the employer is a private enterprise, taxation is used to subsidize parking. As Gordon points out, the provision of "free" parking reduces tax revenues by taking space that could be devoted to tax-generating activities. Other things being equal, the taxes generated by these activities would enable others in society to pay lower taxes. In addition, A 1985 federal law allows employers to subsidize mass transit at the rate of $15 per month; anything over this amount must be added to employees' reported earning for tax purposes. Parking benefits to employees, on the other hand, are not taxed at all. Furthermore, employers can deduct their parking maintenance and operating costs for tax purposes.[40] Thus, taxpayers indirectly subsidize personal-auto commuting. General tax revenues must compensate for taxes lost through parking lot tax deductions. Public transportation enjoys no such tax advantage. In sum, "the real value of 'free' parking... may total more than $85 billion per year."[41] Military expenditures constitute an enormous hidden subsidy of oil-thirsty automotive transport. According to Amory and Hunter Lovins: Earl Ravenal, of the Georgetown University School of Foreign service, found that in fiscal year 1985 alone... the United States spent $47 billion projecting power into the Persian Gulf: $468 per barrel imported from the Gulf in that year, or eighteen times the $27 or so that we paid for the oil itself....[42] When people think of automotive transport, they seldom consider such military expenses as part of the bill that they are paying for the privilege of using a car. Yet if public transportation were developed properly, the United States could eventually eliminate its dependence on foreign sources of oil, and reduce its military budget. The health bill for illnesses associated with air pollution generated by cars and trucks constitutes another hidden subsidy. Costs include not only direct payments from individuals, businesses, and government units for medical attention, but also revenue lost due to workdays missed as a result of illness, permanent disability, or premature death. Paying for medical attention and lost productivity due to the higher accident rate of automotive as opposed to rail transport is yet another hidden subsidy. Highway law enforcement is also a subsidy. Many fewer police are needed to enforce traffic laws against possible violation by the relatively few drivers of public transport. For the most part, highway law enforcement is a hidden subsidy of transportation by car and truck. Road construction in the United States has been highly subsidized from general tax revenues. No comparable subsidy exists for rail or mass transit. "WPA projects in the 1930s, for example, included a strong road-building component; 10 times as much WPA money was spent on street and highway projects as on mass transit."[43] At the same time the federal government began subsidizing a form of housing development, suburban sprawl, that favors the use of cars instead of public transportation. The Federal Housing Administration (FHA), which gave federal guarantees for home mortgages, promoted new construction. According to author James Kunstler, These new houses tended to be located outside the dense cities, because during the Depression vacant land on the periphery was very cheap. The kinds of houses that the FHA frowned upon were those in the cities: old houses with leaky plumbing, jammed into narrow lots on crowded streets, inhabited in some cases by immigrants or, increasingly, African- Americans.[44] Subsidy for this kind of housing persists in the form of the mortgage interest income tax deduction available to homeowners. All things considered, public subsidies for automotive transportation are enormous. Considering just "major costs - including those from [parking,] smog, accidents, and traffic jams -the total U.S. subsidy paid to drivers is estimated to range from $300-$600 billion per year. This is enormously inefficient. But because the subsidies are largely hidden or taken for granted, the cost-inefficiency of cars and trucks is largely unknown. On grounds of transportation efficiency alone, then, it makes sense to do exactly as most environmentalists advise. Identify and phase out subsidies to cars and trucks and increase subsidies for mass transit, especially rail. Subsidize compact development that renders mass transit most useful, and subsidize fast intercity rail. Provide bicycle lanes and paths, as well as pedestrian zones, in cities. The Environment and Environmental Justice Greater transportation efficiency is good for the environment and promotes social justice.[45] As for the environment, transportation efficiency lessens automotive air pollution that harms not only people but wildlife and crops. The energy efficiency of travel by rail, bicycle, and foot reduces the use of fossil fuels that contributes to the greenhouse effect. Because less land is needed for rail and other forms of public transportation, not to mention bicycle and foot, more land is available for preservation of wetlands and other types of wilderness areas. Compact living and working arrangements that accompany efficient modes of transportation augment this effect. Social justice is facilitated by more efficient, public transportation because, as Marcia Lowe points out, "Even in the highly mobile United States, which nearly has a car for every two people, more than ten million households have no motor vehicle."[46] James Kunstler adds that many households and families that have cars are strained by the associated expense. The $4500 it costs to own and operate a car each year could cover a year's payments on a $30,000 mortgage. Often, it is absolutely necessary to keep two cars operating in a family so that two adults can drive long distances to work low-wage jobs. The cost of driving everywhere, to work, or to obtain the necessary goods and services of life, impoverishes families. It makes it impossible for them to own their own home.[47] In sum, it should come as no surprise that relatively inexpensive public transportation is more helpful to poorer than to richer people, and, therefore, that it promotes social equality. Social arrangements that facilitate walking and bicycling also benefit the poor disproportionately, resulting in greater equality. Increased equality is increased social justice in this context because, as noted earlier, equality is presumptively just, and there are no countervailing reasons or values here to rebut that presumption. We no longer think that economic inequality is justified by God's special love for some groups or individuals over others. Instead, we justify inequality primarily as a by-product of free market competition that serves to ameliorate scarcity through efficient use of resources. As I have just argued, however, in the present context efficiency and the amelioration of scarcity are served by mass and public transportation, which also disproportionately aid the poor. This aid therefore advances not only equality, but social justice. Reductions in air pollution that would follow reduced reliance on automotive transport are also disproportionately helpful to the relatively poor. Many poor people inhabit inner cities where excessive traffic congestion, as we have seen, increase and concentrate air pollution from cars and trucks. The resulting illnesses are especially disadvantageous to the poor in the United States because there is no universal health insurance. Any reduction in the use of petrochemicals also disproportionately benefits poor people and people of color, because polluting industries tend to expose such people more than others to toxic substances.[48] Again, in the present context, advantages to the poor constitute increases in justice as well as equality. Because environmental quality is here at issue (air quality and exposure to industrial pollution), these increases in justice constitute improvements in environmental justice. In sum, pursuing the goals of efficiency, environmental protection, and social justice converge in the case of transportation. Limitations of space preclude discussion here of particular proposals for achieving these goals in transportation. PART III - CONCLUSION: EFFICIENCY AND JUSTICE The foregoing means that the generally recognized value of efficiency can be enlisted in the cause of environmentalism and of environmental justice, at least so far as transportation is concerned. I have elsewhere constructed a similar argument regarding agriculture.[49] Such arguments can be made without emphasis on the effects of our actions on future generations, because many of the efficiency, environmental, and justice benefits of environmentally- friendly transportation systems accrue within a single generation. Additional study is required to see how many, and which, other areas of human endeavor, when subject to similar analysis, yield similar conclusions. There is reason to suppose that the confluence noted here is common, if not universal. To the extent that efficiency improvements enable people to get what they want and need from fewer environmental resources, such improvements tend to promote reductions in the burden that people place on the environment. So efficiency improvements tend to be environmentally friendly. For the most part, efficiency improvements probably also promote social and environmental justice. Poor people and people of color generally have less access to environmental resources. Efficiency improvements generally enable people to get more from fewer environmental resources. When human life is so organized that fewer resources are needed, those with access to the fewest resources are generally helped the most. Social justice improves as benefits accrue disproportionately to poor people. Environmental justice improves with reductions in people's disproportionate exposure to deleterious substances, such as toxic pollution. All other things being equal, improvements in efficiency that allow human needs to be met with fewer natural resources may reduce unwanted by-products of human activities, such as toxic pollution. Where poor people are disproportionately exposed to environmental disutilities (as, for the most part, they are), a general decrease in pollution will likely reduce their deleterious exposure to it. These general, theoretical considerations are only suggestive. They are no substitute for case-by-case exploration of confluence among improvements in efficiency, environment, and justice. ENDNOTES [1] See Bryan G. Norton, Toward Unity Among Environmentalists (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991). [2] See Peter S. Wenz, Environmental Justice (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1988). [3] Clement A. Tisdell, Natural Resources, Growth, and Development: Economics, Ecology, and Resource-Scarcity (New York: Praeger Publishers, 1990), pp. 1-2. [4] Gary Gardner, "Shrinking Fields: Cropland Loss in a World of Eight Billion," Worldwatch Paper #131 (July 1996), p. 6. [5] Gardner, pp. 30-31. [6] Gardner, pp. 26-27. [7] See Charles V. Blatz, "General Introduction," Ethics and Agriculture (Moscow, Idaho: University of Idaho Press, 1991), pp. 11-12; and Sandra Postel, "Dividing the Waters: Food Security, Ecosystem health, and the New Politics of Scarcity," WorldWatch Paper #132 (September 1996), especially pp. 17-19. [8] This quote from Lauderdale is from Herman E. Daly and John B. Cobb, Jr., For the Common Good, Second Edition (Boston: Beacon Press, 1994), p. 147. [9] Daly and Cobb, p. 147. [10] Daly and Cobb, 147-148. [11] This example is taken from Peter S. Wenz, Nature's Keeper (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1996), p. 155. [12] Sandra Postel, "Toward a New 'Eco'-Nomics," WorldWatch (September/October 1990), p. 22. [13] Marcia Lowe, "Back on Track: The Global Rail Revival," WorldWatch Paper #118 (April 1994), p. 6. [14] Lowe, p. 13. [15] Deborah Gordon, Steering a New Course: Transportation, Energy, and the Environment (Washington, DC: Island Press, 1991), p. 25. [16] Gordon, p. 25. [17] Gordon, p. 3. Emphasis in the original. [18] Gordon, pp. 42-43. [19] Gordon, p. 46, endnote #11. [20] Lowe, p. 16. [21] Gordon, p. 63. [22] Gordon, p. 64. [23] Gordon, p. 63. [24] Gordon, pp. 40-41. [25] Gordon, pp. 41-42. [26] Gordon, p. 42. [27] Gordon, p. 25. [28] Gordon, p. 25. [29] Lowe, p. 6. [30] Lowe, p. 7. [31] Lowe, p. 7. [32] Lowe, p. 15-16. [33] Lowe, p. 41. [34] Lowe, p. 42. [35] Lowe, p. 41. [36] Gordon, p. 29. [37] Gordon, p. 32. [38] Gordon, p. 142. [39] Gordon, p. 147. [40] Gordon, pp. 148-149. [41] Lowe, p. 35. [42] Found in Daly and Cobb, p. 344. [43] Gordon, p. 11. [44] James Howard Kunstler, The Geography of Nowhere (New York: Touchstone, 1994), p. 102. [45] By "improvements in social justice" I mean in this context greater equality of income, wealth, non-monetary access to needed environmental inputs, and freedom from environmental disutilities such as polluted water and air. I use "environmental justice" as a sub-category of social justice that refers particularly to equality of non-monetary access to needed environmental inputs and freedom from environmental disutilities. [46] Lowe, p. 7. [47] Kunstler, p. 183. [48] See especially M. Lavelle and M. Coyle, "Unequal Protection," National Law Journal, 21 September 1992, pp. 1-2. [49] See "Pragmatism in Practice: The Efficiency of Sustainable Agriculture," forthcoming. Justice and Environmental Justice Justice and Environmental Justice work_klumnarkrzeipinb427bpsmcwq ---- EM-REPS180020 153..175 What empowers Egyptian women: resources versus social constrains? Hanan Nazier and Racha Ramadan Faculty of Economics and Political Science, Cairo University, Giza, Egypt Abstract Purpose – This paper aims to tackle an important question related to women’s economic empowerment in highly patriarchal societies like Egypt. The paper discusses individual, household, wealth and location factors determining women empowerment, as measured by two dimensions: decision-making power and mobility. Design/methodology/approach – Using the “Egypt Labor Market Panel Survey” (ELMPS) 2012, a Multiple Indicators Multiple Causes (MIMIC) model was estimated to study the main economic resources and social constraints that determine women empowerment as measured by the power of women over household decisions and her freedom of movement in Egypt. Findings – Three key messages could be delivered. First, women’s own economic resources as captured by her employment status are an important source of her empowerment. Second, contrary to theoretical prediction education is not playing its expected role in developing awareness and transforming ideas concerning gender roles in Egypt. Third, the importance of social local context is fundamental for Egyptian women empowerment. Originality/value – This study is an attempt to address some of the gaps in the literature for the Egyptian case, where there is a lack in rigorous studies measuring women empowerment and examining its determinates. This is done by first, tackling multiple dimension of women’s empowerment, decision-making inside households and freedom of mobility. Second, using MIMIC model, which is a modeling approach that allows for studying the relations between several causes of a given latent variable, such as “Empowerment” in our case, and a number of its possible indicators, without a directly observable measure of the latent variable. Third, using the most recent set of data; the ELMPS 2012 which has a special focus on women’s resources and agency that permits greater content validity of the multidimensional setup. Forth, the macro level differences in women’s status are tackled through using location dummy variables. Finally, given the important correlation between wealth level and women empowerment, the paper is considered a first attempt to analyze such impact by including a variable that captures the wealth level of the woman’s household as one determinant of empowerment. Keywords MIMIC, Women’s empowerment, Agency empowerment, Decision-making index, Mobility index Paper type Research paper © Hanan Nazier and Racha Ramadan. Published in Review of Economics and Political Science. Published by Emerald Publishing Limited. This article is published under the Creative Commons Attribution (CC BY 4.0) licence. Anyone may reproduce, distribute, translate and create derivative works of this article (for both commercial and non-commercial purposes), subject to full attribution to the original publication and authors. The full terms of this licence may be seen at http:// creativecommons.org/licences/by/4.0/legalcode JEL classification – J16, J12, J60 The authors are thankful to Professor Ragui Assaad for all his valuable comments, suggestions and support. Funding: This work was supported by Economic Research Forum (ERF) [grant numbers: 2013-023]. Resources versus social constrains 153 Received 26 September 2018 Accepted 26 September 2018 Review of Economics and Political Science Vol. 3 No. 3/4, 2018 pp. 153-175 EmeraldPublishingLimited 2631-3561 DOI 10.1108/REPS-10-2018-015 The current issue and full text archive of this journal is available on Emerald Insight at: www.emeraldinsight.com/2631-3561.htm http://dx.doi.org/10.1108/REPS-10-2018-015 Introduction Women’s empowerment refers to their possession of enabling resources, which may, in turn, enhance their agency (Naila. Kabeer, 1999) or ability to “define their own life-choices”, even with opposition from others. Feminist scholars view women’s empowerment as an important goal in itself; whereas, instrumentalists see it as a useful means to achieve other development goals related to health and well-being of empowered women, their children and their household among other societal benefits[1] as well as overall nation economic growth[2]. Accordingly, women’s empowerment has been stressed as a key objective for development policies and programs, as evidenced by the third Millennium Development Goal (MDG) of promoting gender equality and empowering women and then the fifth Sustainable Development Goal with a similar content (Kabeer 2005a). This importance is gaining more emphasis given the positive logic association between poverty and disempowerment, as the inability of providing basic needs often rules out the inability of exercising meaningful choices (Malhotra and Schuler, 2005 and Abdel Mowla, 2009). Hence, formulating women’s empowerment, specifying its dimensions and its determinants as well as standardizing rigorous approaches to its measurement are priorities for global research and policy. The concern with women’s empowerment has also been building in Egypt during the past 30 years, especially after the uprising of the January 25, 2011. These events have heightened societal concerns about women’s role in the public sphere and in economic life, as well as her critical role inside her own household. Women face serious challenges in terms of participation in economic life in Egypt. Women make up only a quarter of the labor force, with almost a quarter of those who are economically active, being unemployed rather than employed, an unemployment rate that is approximately four times higher than that of men. Unemployment is heavily concentrated among young women, approximately 11 per cent of all young women are unemployed, a share higher than among young men, despite lower force participation. Most young women are not in the labor force as 75 per cent of young women are inactive (Assaad and Krafft, 2015). Moreover, poverty in Egypt reached 27.8 per cent in 2014/2015, according to the Central Agency for Public Mobilization and Statistics (CAPMAS). The poor in Egypt are concentrated in rural areas among female-headed households. The MDGs report sheds light on the stronger negative association between school attendance and poverty for girls relative to boys. Only 80 per cent of female children (6-12) in the poorest households have ever attended school compared with 88 per cent of male children in the same age group (UNDP and Ministry of Economic development, 2010). Illiteracy is also strongly associated with gender in Egypt. According to the 2006 population census, among the 2.5 million illiterates between the ages of 15 to 24 in Egypt, 60 per cent were female (Population Census, 2006). There is a general agreement that women’s empowerment is a dynamic, context-specific and multi-dimensional process featuring economic, socio-cultural, familial/interpersonal, legal, political and psychological dimensions. This yields to some challenges when measuring women’s empowerment. From these challenges some are distinguished by the literature to be of most importance; these include the use of proxy indicators instead of direct measures, the lack of the availability and use of data across time, the subjectivity in assessing process and the shifts in relevance of indicators over time (Roushdy, 2004 and Malhotra and Schuler, 2005). Our review of the international literature revealed that with some exceptions (Kishor, 2000a; Yount, 2005), the majority of studies used direct measures of empowerment with a REPS 3,3/4 154 geographical bias toward South Asian countries[3]. For the MENA region, there is a lack of rigorous studies of this kind. Common gaps in the literature at both the international level as well as at the MENA region level include the following. Most research on women’s empowerment used secondary data from multi-purpose surveys, which contain a limited number of empowerment-related items (Kishor and Subaiya, 2008). Most of the studies used summative indices that assign equal weights to different observed indicators of empowerment. Moreover, a common shortcoming of most of the previous studies is ignoring the macro level determinates of women’s status and hence the context specific aspect of empowerment (Durrant and Sathar, 2000; Roushdy, 2004). Finally, none of the studies examined the effect of income/wealth level on women’s empowerment. Therefore, this study is an attempt to address some of those gaps in the literature for the Egyptian case, where there is a lack in rigorous studies measuring women’s empowerment and examining its determinates. This is done by first, tackling multiple dimension of women’s empowerment; decision-making inside households and freedom of mobility. Second, using Multiple Indicators Multiple Causes (MIMIC) model, which is a modeling approach that allows for studying the relations between several causes of a given latent variable, such as “Empowerment” in our case, and a number of its possible indicators, without a directly observable measure of the latent variable. Third, using the most recent set of data; the Egypt Labor Market Panel Survey (ELMPS) 2012 which has a special focus on women’s resources and agency that permits greater content validity of our multidimensional setup. Forth, the macro level differences in women’s status are tackled through using location dummy variables. Finally, given the important correlation between wealth level and women’s empowerment, the paper is considered a first attempt to analyze such impact by including a variable that captures the wealth level of the woman’s household as one determinant of empowerment. Accordingly, this paper is concerned with determinants of women’s empowerment in Egypt. Using the ELMPS 2012, the paper discusses individual, household, wealth and location factors determining women’s empowerment, as measured by two dimensions; decision-making power and mobility. The paper is organized as follows; Section 1 is a background that reviews women’s empowerment measures and the related literature. Section 2 describes the methodology. Section 3 presents the data used in the regression. The estimated results are presented in Section 4 and finally Section 5 concludes. Background 2.1 Defining and measuring women’s empowerment and agency There is a growing body of literature in which efforts have been made to define the concept of empowerment. The present study will adopt the definition introduced by Kabeer (1998, 1999, 2001a, 2001b, 2005a, 2005b), where woman empowerment is defined as the process through which women acquire enabling resources that enhance their agency, which in turn enhance their personal well-being as well as that of their family. Enabling resources include human resources (e.g. school attainment), economic resources (e.g. income or other assets) and social ones (e.g. membership in extra-familial networks) (Kabeer, 1999; 2001b; 2011). Women’s agency means her ability to define and to make strategic life choices. In concept, women agency comprises women’s observable actions and their ideational agency. Women’s observable actions include their influence in family economic decisions and their freedom of movement in public spaces, while their ideational agency refers to their perceptions and views towards equitable gender attitudes (Kabeer, 1999). Accordingly, women’s empowerment is viewed widely as a multidimensional phenomenon that covers various dimensions such as economic, socio-cultural, familial/interpersonal, legal, political Resources versus social constrains 155 and psychological (Kabeer, 1999; Malhotra and Schuler, 2005; Yount, 2005 and Elisabeth Mogford, 2011). In Egypt, the dominant model that governs familial and kin relations is the ideal type model of classic patriarchy (Kandiyoti, 1988). Accordingly, salient aspects of women’s agency in Egypt are identified to be women’s participation in family decisions (especially those reserved for men), freedom of movement in public spaces and vocalization of views favoring more equitable gender roles and rights (Nawar et al., 1995; Govindasamy and Malhotra, 1996; Kishor, 1995, 2000a; Yount, 2005 and Yount et al., 2015). In this study, we focus on women’s observable actions aspect of agency. Accordingly, women’s empowerment is measured by two dimensions; their influence in family’s decisions and their freedom of movement in public spaces. Influence in family decisions indicates the extent of women’s say (none, joint or alone) in household decisions related to monetary transaction, food purchase and her healthcare. By women’s freedom of movement, we mean their ability to go to places, such as the market or the health center (cannot go alone, need permission or does not need permission). Following recent literature, those decisions should not be valued equally. Some of them reflect social norms and pre-existing gender division of roles and responsibilities like the purchase of daily items, what to cook daily and whether permission required to go to market, which are typical female responsibilities. Those decisions reflect a greater responsibility for the family rather than a greater freedom of choices. While other decisions may reflect self-consideration rather than just responsibility such as permission required to visit family and friends, who decides on obtaining health care for respondent and for buying clothes for herself. Meanwhile some of those decisions are minor daily life decisions (e.g. what to cook daily) while others are strategic life choices (like getting medical treatment and large household purchases) (Kabeer, 2001a and Garikipati et al., 2017) that could be considered to reflect a greater freedom of choices. Therefore, it would be inappropriate to merge all decisions in one single measure and they should be analyzed separately. Meanwhile, all these decisions are interdependent, as they are all concerned with the woman’s life within her household. Hence, the paper distinguishes the different decisions and studies them simultaneously through using a MIMIC model as will be explained in details in the methodology section. 2.2 Women’s empowerment measurement As empowerment is a multidimensional concept, it is problematic to operationalize it; this is reflected in some weakness in its measurement in the literature. Some studies used indirect measures using a single observable characteristic, such as women’s education, labor force participation rates and earnings, as a proxy of empowerment. While others used direct measures, which is a combination of observable indicators that are grouped into different dimensions of empowerment including economic decision-making; child-related decision- making; marriage related decision-making; freedom of movement; power relations with husband; access to resources; self-esteem; and control over resources. The indirect measures were extremely criticized (Jejeebhoy, 1991; Balk, 1994; Vlassoff, 1994). First, proxies for empowerment are context dependent, these render comparative research inaccurate. Second, proxy measures do not afford adequate evidence for how well they capture empowerment dimensions. Third, proxies alter the channels through which empowerment works. Finally, as empowerment compromises multiple dimensions, proxies obscure which dimension is being measured (Whyte, 1978 and Agarwala and Lynch, 2006). Direct measures managed to tackle many of the inadequacies of the indirect-measure approach. They have explicitly quantified the mutli-dimensionality of empowerment, thus clarifying the determinants and consequences of each dimension. In addition, direct- REPS 3,3/4 156 measures enlightened the channels through which economic and social factors, such as education and labor force participation, affect empowerment, rather than confusing its causes and effects (Goetz and Gupta, 1996; Mason, 1997; Kritz and Makinwa-Adebusoye, 1999; and Agarwala and Lynch, 2006). 2.3 Theoretical foundations of determinants of women’s economic empowerment Our theoretical foundation for the determinants of women’s empowerment follows Yount (2005). Economics and population studies imply that the distribution of power in marriage depends on the balance of economic and social resources between husbands and wives (Jr, Robert O Blood and Donald M Wolf, 1960). However, empirical studies show that the effect of husband’s economic resources on marital power depends on the institutional and normative context (Hyman Rodman, 1972). In Middle East patriarchal societies, husbands or marital kin control major decisions; hence, ascribed characteristics are more important than economic resources as sources of power for husbands and marital kin. Accordingly, husband’s and household economic resources are irrelevant to patterns of decision-making in marriage (Rodman, 1972). Meanwhile, those studies confirm the positive effect of a woman’s economic resources on her marital power through different normative and institutional contexts (Fox, 1973; Burr et al., 1977; Rogler et al., 1982; Oropesa, 1997; Xu and Shu-Chuan, 2002). Hence, access to and control over social and economic resources within and beyond the marital home may influence women’s empowerment. Moreover, in patriarchal settings prescribed powers of husbands and marital relatives provide them authority over family decisions and are more important than their economic resources as sources of power. Accordingly, at one hand, social and economic resources that women have are expected to affect their influence in family decisions and hence their empowerment. However, on the other hand, social constrains, mainly the structure of a woman’s marital household and local social context where she lives, can constrain her decisions (Yount, 2005). Following Yount (2005), the main determinants of women’s empowerment resulting from this conceptual framework can be summarized into four groups. First, social resources that include woman’s age and parents’ characteristics. Second, economic resources include human capital (e.g. educational attainment, employment) and wealth. Third, social constraints – refers to the social restrictions on woman’s ability to use resources available to her and include age and education gaps between husband and wife. The fourth group includes regional dummy variables to account for local social context. In light of the previous discussion, we propose three main hypotheses: H1. Living with a parent-in-law or an adult son and higher age difference with husband will decrease a woman’s impact on decisions as well as her mobility. While having greater number of children will increase her decision-making power and decrease her mobility. H2. Economic resources of husbands (measured by his education and employment status) and of the household (reflected by household standard of living) will be irrelevant to a woman’s decision-making power and mobility. H3. Increases in a woman’s access to and control over social and economic resources (parents characteristics, her own and her parent’s contribution to marriage costs, woman’s employment and education status) will increase her decisions making power and mobility. While woman’s age increases her decisions making power but decreases her mobility. Resources versus social constrains 157 2.4 Empirical evidence of women’s economic empowerment in Egypt Few studies examined quantitatively women’s empowerment determinants in Egypt. Several methodological approaches were used, such as descriptive approach and probability models. Probability models (logit, probit, ordered logit) allows testing the realization of empowerment using a specific indicator, for instance whether the woman is employed (i.e. empowered). To tackle the multidimensionality of women’s empowerment; factor analysis is used to reflect the several dimensions of empowerment in one indicator. MIMIC model is used as well to allow tackling the multidimensionality of women’s empowerment. Of the studies focusing on indirect measures of empowerment, Khattab and Sakr (2009) used the descriptive approach and the ELMPS (2006) to investigate determinates of women’s empowerment in Egypt. This study focused on the economic dimension of women’s empowerment as measured indirectly by female participation in the labor market. Abdel Mowla (2009) also used indirect measures of empowerment obtained from the ELMPS (2006). The author applied logistic regression to examine the effect of the level and type of education on women economic empowerment proxied by two indirect measures: (1) economic participation; measured as female labor force participation, probability of escaping employment and strengthening job search behavior; and (2) economic opportunity; measured by wage work and escaping vulnerable employment, escaping low quality job and overcoming occupational segregation. Other studies used indirect measures. Kishor (1995) estimated ordered logit model using the 1988 Egypt Demographic and Health Survey (EDHS) to examine the effect of several modernization, economic and cultural factors on three different direct measures of empowerment. First, the customary autonomy index used to measure the extent to which women believe they should have the say in decision related to matters women traditionally would have control over; mainly family planning and children education and marriage. Second, the non-customary autonomy index that measures the extent to which women believe they should have decision-making powers in general and in areas outside their traditional roles, such as visits to relatives and household’s budget. Finally, the realized autonomy index measuring the extent to which women perceive that they have decision- making powers and freedom of movement. The determinants of empowerment used by this study are household characteristics (region and socio-economic index), individual characteristics (age, education exposure to media, migration history and employment status), husband characteristics (education and profession) and cultural variables (religion, marriage pattern, post marital residential arrangement and number of children by gender). The results showed that while most factors have a similar impact on the indices of customary autonomy and non-customary autonomy, they do not always have the same impact on the realized autonomy index. Modernization efforts that affect women’s individual characteristics, like women own education, affect women mostly by altering their views about women’s role in decision-making. While modernization efforts that affect the circumstances in which women live, such as the level of education of her husband, affect her realized level of autonomy. The impact of employment on empowerment is different for each dimension. Realized autonomy is the only aspect that is significantly affected by women work, irrespective of whether they control their earnings and whether they earn cash for the work they do. The other two dimensions as measures of perceptions about women’s roles is not affected by employment per se, but by access to, and control over, earnings derived from employment. Finally, only few cultural variables affect any of the aspects of empowerment REPS 3,3/4 158 directly, realized autonomy is lower among women who are Muslim, who live in large households, who are remarried and who have greater number of children irrespective of their gender. The factor analysis approach is used by Yount (2005) to create scales capturing women’s say in household decisions and examined the impact of a woman’s social and economic resources and household structure on her family power and gender preferences in Minya, Egypt. Marital household structure mainly residence with parents-in-law, brothers-in-law and the husband decrease women’s influence in decisions. Social resources had a significant impact on women decision-making; on average, women in endogamous marriages have greater influence in life course decisions than do women in non-endogamous marriages and women’s age is significantly associated only with having greater influence in daily domestic decisions. Economic resources impact depends on the variable used to capture it, while her own education and work as well as her husband education had a significant positive impact on daily and life course decisions; wealth measures had no significant effect. Similarly, Yount et al. (2016) used factor analysis to explore the multi-dimensionality of Egyptian women’s agency. They focused on the effect of women’s age at first marriage on her empowerment. They used the ELMPS 2006 and applied factor analysis to explore and test the factor structure of women’s agency on three main dimensions: family decisions, freedom of movement and acceptance of violence against wives. They used as well MIMIC structural equations model to test for Differential Item Functioning (DIF) by women’s age at first marriage. Results showed that women’s older age at first marriage was positively associated with family decision-making power and gender-violence attitudes, but not freedom of movement, thus confirming the multidimensional aspect of women’s empowerment. Finally, Salem et al. (2017) studied the impact of ever-married women’s market work compared to those with subsistence work and those who do not work on women’s empowerment in rural Minya, Egypt. They focused on three dimensions of empowerment: economic decision-making, freedom of movement and equitable gender role attitudes. Using structural equation model with propensity score adjustment, the results showed that women’s work has a positive impact on women’s freedom of movement where the effect of market work exceed that of subsistence work. But women’s work does not affect decision- making power or gender attitudes. However, those studies have some limitations. First, despite using direct measurement for empowerment most of them focused on a single dimension of empowerment decision- making with the exception of Kishor (1995), Yount (2016) and Salem et al. (2017). Still these later two studies focused on the impact of a single factor [age at marriage for Yount (2016) and woman’s work for Salem et al. (2017)] on empowerment. In addition, Yount (2016) used relatively old data set, while Salem et al. (2017) used a subsample of only 600 women. Second, a common shortcoming of most of the previous studies is ignoring the macro level differences of the community where the woman lives (Durrant and Sathar, 2000; Roushdy, 2004). Finally, none of the studies reviewed examined the effect of wealth level on women’s empowerment. Hence, this research is an attempt to address those limitations. First, we use the most available recent data set to tackle multiple dimension of women’s empowerment in the same analysis namely, two dimensions of women’s empowerment are studied; mobility and decision-making inside households. More precisely, using the ELMPS (2012), the paper focused on the determinants of women’s empowerment in Egyptian households. Second, we measure women’s empowerment using a measurement modeling approach that allows for differential weighting in the relationship of latent empowerment variable with the observed items. Third, the macro level differences in women’s status are tackled through using Resources versus social constrains 159 location variables[4]. Finally, given the important correlation between poverty and women’s empowerment, our analysis includes a variable that captures the wealth status of the woman’s household as one determinant of empowerment. 3. Methodology This paper uses the MIMIC Model, which is used when there are several causes and several indicators for a single latent variable (Joreskog and Goldberger, 1975). In our case, this latent variable is women’s empowerment in Egypt, noted as E*. The different determinants of empowerment include social resources, social constraints, economic resources and demographic variables. Then empowerment affect the decision-making power of the respondent within her household as well as her freedom of mobility. The decision-making power and the freedom of mobility are represented in our model by several decision and mobility indicators (See Appendix 1). The advantage of using a MIMIC model is that it allows exploring the linkages between the determinants of our latent variable, empowerment, and several its indicators, without a directly observable measure of empowerment (Rose and Spiegel, 2009). Moreover, the MIMIC model allows considering simultaneously different empowerment indicators, which are the different decisions in our case, in addition to accounting for the interdependence between these decisions. More precisely, the MIMIC model consists of estimating two interdependent sets of structural equations. The first is a structural equation that models the causes of the latent variable empowerment (E*). As empowerment variable, E*, takes value 1 if woman is empowered, 0 otherwise, the structural equation can be written as follows, where the f(.) is logit function, Xs are the different causes of empowerment and the error term « follow logistic distribution. P E* ¼ 1ð Þ ¼ f X1; . . . :; Xk; «ð Þ (1) The regressors X include the causes of empowerment that can be divided into four groups: social resources, economic resources, social constraints and demographic characteristics. Following the literature, the respondent’s social and economic resources include her age in years and its square –to take into consideration, the non-linear effect of age- her education and her employment status. To account for the fact that woman empowerment could be affected by her employment status and vice versa which may cause a problem of endogeniety; the employment status of the respondent in 2006 is used instead of her current employment status. As it is expected that being employed in 2006 may affect her actual level of empowerment in 2012, but the inverse is not true. Other social and economic resources include her parents’ employment status, her share and her family’s share in the marriage costs. This group of determinates include also a dummy variable for wealth quintiles based on wealth score that accounts for the durable goods available to the household. To control for social constraints, we include variables, such as the number of her children, if there is an adult son living with her and if she is living with her mother in law. Moreover, to take into account the role that maybe played by the respondent’s husband characteristics in affecting her decision-making power and her freedom of movement, his age and education gap between him and her (age gap) are included in the model. In addition to the education gap that reflects if both have same education, if he has higher education by one level, two or more levels and if he has lower education by one level, two or more levels. Her husband’s employment status is included in the model as well. Finally, the model includes regional dummies of the five Egyptian regions where the respondent lives, to control for the social context where the respondent lives. REPS 3,3/4 160 The second, set of equations is the indicators equations, which are the outputs of empowerment. In our cases, we have ten indicator equations; six for the decision-making power, DIi, for who have the say concerning issues as large household’s purchases, daily food and purchase of her clothes. And four mobility indicators, MIj, which are tackling her ability to visit sites such as the local market or health centers. Each variable of DIi and MIj may take several answers based on who takes the decision and based on the ability to go out with or without permission from other family members, respectively. For instance, concerning the decision indicators, women may take decisions alone, with others or do not participate at all. Hence, each decision indicator is assigned the highest rank if she takes the decision alone, followed by women who decide jointly with their husbands then come those who decide jointly with others in their household and finally women who have no say in the decision. Similarly, for mobility indicators, she may be able to go out without the need of permission, by just informing them or with someone from the households[5]. Accordingly, DIi and MIj are two sets of observable indicators of empowerment, which take ordered values, hence, the second set of structural equations can be written as follows, where the gi (.) and fj (.) are ordered logit and the errors terms mi; �i follow logistic distribution: DIi ¼ gi E*; m i � � ; i ¼ 1; 2; ::::6 (2A) MIj ¼ fj E*; vj � � ; j ¼ 1; 2; ::::4 (2B) 4. Data The data used in this paper are drawn from the Egyptian labor Market Panel Survey (ELMPS) for 2012. The ELMPS is carried out by the Economic Research Forum (ERF) in cooperation with Egypt’s Central Agency for Public Mobilization and Statistics (CAPMAS) since 1998. The ELMPS 2012 is the third round of this periodic longitudinal survey that tracks the labor market and the demographic characteristics of households and individuals interviewed in 2006, both individuals included in the ELMS 1998 and individuals added in 2006, as well as a refresher sample of 2,000 new households to ensure that the data continues to be nationally representative, a total sample of 12,060 households and 49,186 individuals. The ELMPS is considered a wide-ranging, nationally representative panel survey that covers topics such as parental background, education, housing, access to services, residential mobility, migration and remittances, time use, marriage patterns and costs, fertility, women’s decision making and empowerment, job dynamics, savings and borrowing behavior, the operation of household enterprises and farms, besides the usual focus on employment, unemployment and earnings in typical labor force surveys. Our research focuses on 5,222 married women, in 5,181 households, aged between 15 and 49 years old, with an average age of 33 years old[6]. Regarding social constraints, only 5 per cent of the respondents live with their mother in law and 22 per cent are living with their adult son. Only 21 per cent of the respondents were employed in 2006. Most of the respondents (93 per cent) are married with men older than them. While, only 30 per cent are married to men with higher education level compared with 20 per cent of the respondents married to men with lower education level. Regarding the economic resources; it is found that 18 and 18 per cent of the sample is in the poorest and richest quintiles, respectively (Table I). While for other demographic characteristics, Table II shows that 17 per cent of the sample lives in metropolitan areas: Resources versus social constrains 161 Great Cairo, Alexandria and Suez Canal. The remaining is distributed between Lower and Upper Egypt in both rural and urban areas, with more than 50 per cent of the sample living in the rural. As described above, women’s empowerment is measured here by decision-making power and mobility indices. Figures 1 and 2 show the distribution of the answers of our sample of interest for each of the questions of decision-making index and mobility index, respectively. Table I. Sample distribution according to wealth quintiles Wealth quintile (%) The poorest 18 Second quintile 20 Third quintile 22 Fourth quintile 20 The richest 18 Total 100 Source: Computed by the authors from ELMPS (2012) Table II. Distribution of the sample by regions Region (%) Metropolitan 17 Urban Lower 12 Urban Upper 15 Rural Lower 31 Rural Upper 25 Total 100 Source: Computed by the authors from ELMPS (2012) Figure 1. Distribution of answers for the decision-making questions (%) REPS 3,3/4 162 For the decision-making questions, we found that, women mainly have a say in the daily decisions; such as daily purchases and what should be cooked daily. For large household’s purchases, visits to family and friends, getting medical treatment for herself and buying clothes to herself, most of women in our sample take these decisions with their husbands (Figure 1). For the mobility dimension, most of women of our sample need permission before going to the local market (48 per cent) or to the health center (54 per cent), before taking children to the health center (55 per cent) or visiting families and friends (65 per cent). It is worth noting that going to the local health center is the most restricted place for Egyptian women in our sample as 31 per cent of our sample cannot go alone as compared to 16, 28 and 18 per cent of the sample cannot go alone to local market, take children to health center and go to friends or relative house, respectively (Figure 2). 5. Empirical results The MIMIC model was estimated using the ELMPS (2012) data for Egypt, our latent variable Empowerment had significant (p < 0.01) factor loadings on all six decision-making power indicators (equal to or exceeding 1.580) as well as the four mobility indictors (equal to or exceeding 1.195) (Appendix 3 and 4). The estimated results for the decision-making index and mobility index are represented in Table III. The two models include variables measuring economic resources, social resources, social constraints and regional variables. For the social resources; the results show that age has a non-linear effect on empowerment as measured by both decision-making power and mobility. Women’s decision-making power and freedom of mobility increased with age until 40 and 37 years old, respectively, then decreased. For parents’ employment, the results showed that father’s employment has a positive significant effect on his daughter empowerment as measured by her mobility. While for her decision-making power only a wage worker father significantly increases his daughter’s empowerment as compared to a no job or unpaid family worker father. As found by the literature, mother’s employment plays an important role in strengthening her daughter’s empowerment. Our results suggest that an employed mother – no matter the type of employment – as compared with mothers with no job had a positive and significant impact on her daughter’s empowerment Figure 2. Distribution of answers for the mobility questions (%) Resources versus social constrains 163 Table III. Estimated coefficients of the decision power and mobility regressions Decision Mobility Empowerment Empowerment Social resources Respondent’s age 0.0463*** (0.010) 0.0559*** (0.0123) Respondent’s age squared �0.001*** (0.000) �0.000754*** (0.000186) Father’s employment status (Reference category: unpaid family worker/no job) Wage worker 0.133* (0.072) 0.198** (0.0855) Employer 0.117 (0.073) 0.186** (0.0874) Self-employed 0.113 (0.076) 0.149* (0.0900) Mother’s employment status (Reference category: no job) Wage worker 0.087** (0.037) 0.0354 (0.0439) Employer/self-employed 0.209*** (0.073) 0.0600 (0.0860) Unpaid family worker 0.173*** (0.044) 0.0905* (0.0521) Share of marriage cost 0.146*** (0.055) 0.147** (0.0658) Economic resources Respondent’s education (Reference category: Illiterate) Literate/Basic – Intermediate Education �0.012 (0.029) 0.0291 (0.0343) Secondary education 0.019 (0.029) 0.00358 (0.0342) Post-Secondary – Post University Education �0.005 (0.038) �0.0692 (0.0453) Respondent was employed in 2006 0.060*** (0.023) 0.0470* (0.0268) Respondent’s wealth status (Reference Category: First quintile) Second quintile 0.0310 (0.025) 0.00405 (0.0298) Third quintile 0.018 (0.024) 0.0246 (0.0284) Fourth quintile 0.008 (0.025) �0.00854 (0.0300) Fifth quintile 0.014 (0.00913) �0.0220** (0.0109) Social constraints Are you daughter in law? �0.330*** (0.0429) �0.121** (0.0493) Do you have an adult son living with you? 0.0900*** (0.0335) �0.0180 (0.0395) Number of children 0.00124 (0.00702) 0.0619*** (0.00873) Age gap between the respondent and her husband (Reference Category: he is older than her) He is younger than her 0.00677 (0.0440) 0.0738 (0.0525) He has the same age as her 0.0574 (0.0488) 0.0199 (0.0580) Education gap between the respondent and her husband (Reference Category: they have the same education level) He has higher education by two or more levels �0.0410 (0.0388) �0.130*** (0.0465) He has higher education by one level �0.0201 (0.0231) �0.0699** (0.0276) He has lower education by two or more levels 0.0136 (0.0483) 0.00401 (0.0576) He has lower education by one level 0.0327 (0.0261) 0.0223 (0.0311) Husband’s employment status (reference category: no job) Wage worker �0.0376 (0.0358) �0.00578 (0.0424) Employer/self employed �0.0710* (0.0386) �0.0821* (0.0456) Demographic characteristics Regional residence (reference category: Metropolitan region) Urban Lower region �0.126*** (0.0332) 0.0342 (0.0392) Urban Upper Region �0.416*** (0.0353) �0.144*** (0.0379) Rural Lower Region �0.178*** (0.0283) 0.0404 (0.0327) Rural Upper Region �0.415*** (0.0352) �0.120*** (0.0378) Observations 5,222 5,222 Notes: Standard errors in parentheses; ***p < 0.01, ** p < 0.05, * p < 0.1 REPS 3,3/4 164 as measured by decision-making power. However, the impact on decision-making power is more pronounced than on mobility. Finally, her own contribution and her parents’ contribution to marriage costs had a positive impact on empowerment as measured by the two indicators. However, social resources do not have the same impact on mobility as on decision-making power. Concerning economic resources; all education categories -as compared to being illiterate- were found to have no significant effect on our two dimensions of empowerment. This surprising result may be explained by the fact that the education system in Egypt is not playing the expected role in transforming ideas and norms of the society towards more equitable gender roles. While for the respondent’s employment status, our results showed that being employed in 2006 has a significant positive impact on the respondent’s two empowerment’s dimensions. Her households’ wealth level has no significant impact on the respondent decision making index. But being in the fifth wealth quintile decreases her mobility. Social constraints are playing an important role in Egyptian women’s empowerment. Living with her mother in law decreases her decision-making power and mobility. While living with an adult son had a positive and significant effect on the decision-making power but a negative insignificant effect on mobility. The number of children a woman has can be considered as an asset for her empowerment; the higher the number of her children the more empowered she is, when empowerment is measured by mobility. However, it has a positive but insignificant effect on empowerment as measured by decision-making power. Concerning husband’s characteristics., the age gap between the respondent and her husband has no significant impact on her two dimensions of empowerment. Generally, as compared to a respondent whose husband has same education level, being married to a more educated husband than herself has a negative effect on empowerment. This effect was significant for women’s mobility but insignificant for her say in the household. While a husband with a lower level of education has a positive but insignificant effect on his wife’s two dimensions of empowerment. It is worth noting that those results hold no matter how much higher or lower is the level of education of husbands compared to his wife. Concerning a husband’s employment, an employed husband as compared to an unemployed husband has a negative impact on his wife two measures of empowerment. However, this effect is only significant for the employer or self-employed husband. Finally, the model includes regional dummies for four of the five Egyptian regions covered by our survey. Given the heterogeneity between the different Egyptian regions, including these dummies, allows capturing the characteristic of the community where she lives. For the decision-making aspect, women living in any of the four Egyptian regions included in our model are less empowered as compared to those who live in Metropolitan area. While for the mobility aspect, respondents living in Upper Egypt, rural or urban, are less empowered compared to their metropolitan counterparts. It worth noting that another version of the two models was estimated without the regional dummies[7]. Comparing the results of the two versions of each model shows that context, measured by regional dummies, was found to be an important determinant of women’s empowerment. It was also found that including the regional dummies, to reflect the context where she lives, affects the impact of the economic resources on women’s empowerment. Without the regional dummies, being in the third or fifth wealth quintile would increase the respondent’s decision-making power. And being in the third wealth quintiles will increase her mobility compared with respondent in the first quintile. Moreover, Resources versus social constrains 165 the presence of the regional dummies in the model affects the role played by her father’s employment and by the education gap between her and her husband on her decision-making power. Such results show that when the community and the social context where the women lives are captured by the model, they play a more significant role in the Egyptian women’s empowerment, compared with the economic and social resources. To sum up, we can conclude that our results came in line with the literature; age, employment, parents’ employment and community context appeared as significant determinants of empowerment. Further, most of these determinants, showed varying impact depending on the dimension of empowerment studied. 6. Discussions and conclusion This study tackles the question of women’s empowerment in highly patriarchal societies like Egypt. Specifically, the study tries to answer the following question: which resources and social constraints determine women’s empowerment as measured by the power of women over household decisions and her freedom of movement? Based on our theoretical framework, we proposed three hypotheses. Findings partially support H1 in the case of power over household decisions, being a daughter in-law, decrease a woman’s decision-making power while living with an adult son increase it and surprisingly increase in number of children is irrelevant. Findings with regards to being a daughter in-law are also consistent with other studies (Balk, 1994; Yount, 2005). For mobility, results were more consistent with hypothesis (1) living with parents-in-law and having more children decrease woman freedom of movement while living with an adult son has no effect. One explanation for the positive effect of living with an adult son on decision-making power is that according to Egyptian norms and culture, being the mother of a son gives the woman more prestige and power as compared with those without a son. It is also common that being the mother of a married son give her more power relative to her daughter-in-law. Concerning economic resources, husband’s education results for the decision-making power came in line with H2 education status of husbands was irrelevant for his wife’s decision-making while for mobility contrary to H2 women whose husbands have a higher level of education as compared to those whose husbands have same level of education have lower mobility. Furthermore, not totally in line with H2, husbands’ employment status effect depends on the husband’s type of employment. Compared to a no job husband, husbands who are employer or self-employed had a negative effect on both decision-making power and mobility of his wife while wageworker husbands have no effect (this wage worker case matches H2). Concerning household’s wealth, results for decision-making power came in line with H2 as wealth was irrelevant for that dimension but for mobility only richest woman are less mobile than those in the poorest quintile. These results suggest that H2 is applicable for decision-making power while it is less applicable for mobility. That is husbands’ economic resources as measured, by his education and employment status, and of the household, as reflected by household standard of living, are irrelevant to a woman’s decision-making power i.e. overt power. While for mobility, i.e. covert power, it has a more pronounced negative effect. This could be explained by the nature of patriarchal communities and the dominant influence of norms and traditions in such communities where husbands would care about social image vis-à-vis the society, so this is reflected on restricted mobility (covert power) of wives in the same time where it is irrelevant when it comes to household decisions (overt power) which is less exposed to the external society. These results also highlight the multidimensional aspect of women’s REPS 3,3/4 166 empowerment as various factors have different effects on different empowerment dimensions. Contrary to H3, formal education was found to be irrelevant for both household decisions and mobility. On the other hand, and consistent with H3, employed women have higher decision-making power and higher freedom of movement. The higher the women’s and her family’s contribution to marriage costs, the higher her empowerment. Moreover, parents’ characteristics had an important positive role. Employed fathers increase his daughter’s empowerment however the effect was more relevant for mobility. In line with the literature, employed mothers also increase daughter’s empowerment, but mother’s employment had a stronger effect than father’s employment. Moreover, contrary to father’s employment the effect of mother employment was more pronounced for decision-making power compared to mobility. Such results suggest that women’s empowerment is more affected by resources, both economic and social, than constraints. Moreover, the effect differs according to type of resources; employment status, share in marriage costs and her parents’ characteristics are more influential and more relevant to women’s empowerment than women’s access to non- customary resources like formal education. Several explanations could be proposed here. First, this may be explained by the fact that what really matters to empowerment is control over resources and actual earnings i.e. that a woman earn income independently which is captured by the share in marriage costs and employment status and not education. This could be especially true given the fact that in Egypt although women have relatively been doing very well when it comes to education in recent years, their labor force participation rates are very low. Hence, females’ education in Egypt is not translated to earnings. Second, although it is believed that empowerment is related to awareness, norms and ideas that could be formed or transformed through education, in Egypt education system suffers from various challenges related to quality that may hinder this role. Previous studies point out that less than 50 per cent of ever-married Egyptian women of reproductive age agree that education is a mean to prepare women for marriage not only for work (El-Zanaty et al., 1996). Finally, social context as captured by the regional dummies is found to have a significant impact on both dimensions of woman empowerment investigated. Not only living in any region in Egypt as compared to greater Cairo decreased both woman decision-making power and mobility but also the impact of other factors on both dimensions was affected. Therefore, in addition to the individual, households, socio demographic and socio-economic characteristics, local context should be considered when analyzing determinants of women’s empowerment. Hence, future research tackling this issue should focus on the regional and social context. This later should not only be captured by the regional dummies; other regional characteristics should be included to determine the channels through which context can affect women’s empowerment. Accordingly, the results of this study provide evidences concerning the conditions under which Egyptian women’s empowerment could be enhanced and translated into improved life chances for them. Three key messages could be delivered in that regard. First, women own economic resources as captured by her employment status are an important source of her empowerment. Second, contrary to theoretical prediction education is not playing its expected role in developing awareness and transforming ideas concerning gender roles in a patriarchal society like Egypt. Third, the importance of social local context is fundamental. Legal, social and institutional arrangements reinforce both women and men’s perceptions of gender roles and the benefits of patriarchal relationship in societies like Egypt. Resources versus social constrains 167 Consequently, policies should work on encouraging female education and reforming the educational system by augmenting it with materials that transform local ideas to redefine the boundaries of women’s lawful social identity beyond patriarchal relationships, reshape perception of gender roles to be more equitable. Moreover, female labor force participation and employment should be encouraged, hence policies should reform labor markets so that women have greater flexibility in the timing of marriage and employment, enhance female entrepreneurial skills and facilitate their access to finance so that women’s productive work is considered as compatible to that of men. Finally, since women’s empowerment is a multi- dimension phenomenon it should be tackled with caution and cannot be grouped or aggregated. Formulating policies to enhance women’s empowerment in Egypt need to tackle different dimensions separately where some policies may be appropriate for tackling various dimensions while others would only tackle specific ones. For instance, tackling the freedom of movement dimension requires increasing access to safe means of transportation and providing services such as street lighting and nearby childcare. While both the decision- making power and the freedom of movement dimensions require policies and actions targeting raising awareness of the importance of women’s role in the household and the whole community. Such campaigns should be provided by the different stakeholders; the government, the civil society, schools and universities, international organizations and the religious personnel whom should all cooperate with female community leaders who are in closer contact with women, especially in rural areas. Notes 1. Hoddinott and Haddad 1995; Roushdy 2004; Kishor and Gupta 2004; Namoro and Roushdy 2009; and Upadhyay and Karasek 2010. 2. Anderson and Eswaran 2009; Malhotra and Schuler 2005; and Yount et al. 2015. 3. (Hashemi et al. (1996); Malhotra and Mather (1997); Mason (1998); Zaman (1999); Jejeebhoy (2000); Mason and Smith (2000); Jejeebhoy and Sathar (2001); Parveen and Leonhäuser (2005); Kamal and Zunaid (2006); Gupta and Yesudian (2006); 200 Allendorf (7); Anderson and Eswaran (2009); Khan and Awan (2011); Varghese, 2011). 4. The macro level determinants are investigated further in Assaad et al. (2015), where we measured those determinates using community level variables that capture norms and traditions. 5. More details about the decision-making indicators and mobility indicators and their answers are available in Appendix 2. 6. Questions related to decision-making and mobility were asked to married women aged between 15 and 49 years old. 7. The estimated results of the model without the regional dummies are presented in Appendix E. References Abdel Mowla, S. (2009), “Education and economic empowerment of women in Egypt”, American University in Cairo – Social Research Center, Working Paper No. 002. Agarwala, R. and Lynch, S.M. (2006), “Refining the measurement of women’s autonomy: an international application of a multi-dimensional construct”, Social Forces, Vol. 84 No. 4, pp. 2077-2098. Allendorf, K. (2007), “Do women’s land rights promote empowerment and child health in Nepal?”, World Development, Vol. 35 No. 11, pp. 1975-1988. REPS 3,3/4 168 Anderson, S. and Eswaran, M. (2009), “What determines female autonomy? Evidence from Bangladesh”, Journal of Development Economics, Vol. 90 No. 2, pp. 179-191. Assaad, R. and Kraft, C. (2015), “The structure and evolution of employment in Egypt: 1998-2012”, The Egyptian Labor Market in an Era of Revolution, pp. 27-51. Assaad, R., Nazier, N. and Ramadan, R. (2015), “Empowerment is a community affair: community level determinants of married women’s empowerment in Egypt”, Economic Research Working paper no 959, October. Balk, D. (1994), “Individual and community aspects of women’s status and fertility in rural Bangladesh”, Population Studies, Vol. 48 No. 1, pp. 21-45. Burr, W.R., Ahern, L. and Knowles, E.M. (1977), “An empirical test of Rodman’s theory of resources in cultural context”, Journal of Marriage and the Family, Vol. 39 No. 3, pp. 505-514. Durrant, V.L. and Sathar, Z.A. (2000), “Greater investments in children through women’s empowerment”, A Key to Demographic Change in Pakistan?, Population Council. Egyptian Labor Market Panel Survey (2012), Egyptian Labor Market Panel Survey, Economic Research Forum, Cairo. Fox, G.L. (1973), “Another look at the comparative resources model: assessing the balance of power in turkish marriages”, Journal of Marriage and the Family, Vol. 35 No. 4, pp. 718-730. Garikipati, S., Isabelle, A., Isabelle, G. and Szafarz, A. (2017), “The cost of empowerment: multiple sources of women’s debt in rural India”, The Journal of Development Studies, Vol. 53 No. 5, pp. 700-722. Goetz, A.M. and Gupta, R.S. (1996), “Who takes the credit? Gender, power, and control over loan use in rural credit programs in Bangladesh”, World Development, Vol. 24 No. 1, pp. 45-63. Govindasamy, P. and Malhotra, A. (1996), “Women’s position and family planning in Egypt”, Studies in Family Planning, Vol. 27 No. 6, pp. 328-340. Gupta, K. and Yesudian, P.P. (2006), “Evidence of women’s empowerment in India: a study of socio- spatial disparities”, GeoJournal, Vol. 65 No. 4, pp. 365-380. Hashemi, S.M., Schuler, S.R. and Riley, A.P. (1996), “Rural credit programs and women’s empowerment in Bangladesh”, World Development, Vol. 24 No. 4, pp. 635-653. Hoddinott, J. and Haddad, L. (1995), “Does female income share influence household expenditures? Evidence from Côte d’Ivoire”, Oxford Bulletin of Economics and Statistics, Vol. 57 No. 1, pp. 77-96. Jejeebhoy, S.J. (1991), “Women’s status and fertility: successive cross-sectional evidence from Tamil Nadu, India, 1970-80”, Studies in Family Planning, Vol. 22 No. 4, pp. 217-230. Jejeebhoy, S.J. (2000), “Women’s autonomy in rural India: its dimensions, determinants, and the influence of context”, In Women‘s Empowerment and Demographic Processes: Beyond Cairo, Eds Presser, Harriet, and Gita Sen, Oxford University Press, New York, NY. Jejeebhoy, S.J. and Sathar, Z.A. (2001), “Women’s autonomy in India and Pakistan: the influence of religion and region”, Population and Development Review, Vol. 27 No. 4, pp. 687-712. Joreskog, K.G. and Goldberger, A.S. (1975), “A estimating model with multiple indicators and multiple causes of a single latent variable”, Journal of the American Statistical Association, Vol. 70 No. 351, pp. 631-639. (September. 1975). Kabeer, N. (1998), “Education is my daughter’s future”, Index on Censorship, Vol. 27 No. 3, pp. 154-160. Kabeer, N. (1999), “Resources, agency, achievements: reflections on the measurement of women’s empowerment”, Development and Change, Vol. 30 No. 3, pp. 435-464. Kabeer, N. (2001a), “Reflections on the measurement of women’s empowerment”, Discussing Women’s Empowerment: Theory and Practice. Sida Studies 3, Novum Grafiska AB, Stockholm. Kabeer, N. (2001b), “Conflicts over credit: re-evaluating the empowerment potential of loans to women in rural Bangladesh”, World Development, Vol. 29 No. 1, pp. 63-84. Resources versus social constrains 169 Kabeer, N. (2005a), “Gender equality and women’s empowerment: a critical analysis of the third millennium development goal 1”, Gender and Development, Vol. 13 No. 1, pp. 13-24. Kabeer, N. (2005b), “Is microfinance a‘magic bullet’ for women’s empowerment? Analysis of findings from South Asia”, Economic and Political Weekly, pp. 4709-4718. Kabeer, N. (2011), “Between affiliation and autonomy: navigating pathways of women’s empowerment and gender justice in rural Bangladesh”, Development and Change, Vol. 42 No. 2, pp. 499-528. Kamal, N. and Zunaid, K.M. (2006), “Education and Women’s Empowerment in Bangladesh”, Working Paper 11, Centre for Health, Population and Development (CHPD), Independent University, Bangladesh. Kandiyoti, D. (1988), “Bargaining with patriarchy”, Gender and Society, Vol. 2 No. 3, pp. 274-290. Khan, U. and Awan, S.R. (2011), “Contextual assessment of women’s empowerment and its determinants: evidence from Pakistan”, MPRA No. 30820, Bond University, Australia. Khattab, A. and Sakr, H. (2009), “Women’s economic empowerment in Egypt: challenges and opportunities”, Social Research Center Working Paper No. 001. Kishor, S. (1995), “Autonomy and Egyptian women: findings from the 1988 Egypt demographic and health survey”, Occasional Papers 2, Macro International Inc, Calverton, MD. Kishor, S. (2000a), “Empowerment of women in Egypt and links to the survival and health of their infants”, “in Women‘s Empowerment and Demographic Processes: Beyond Cairo, eds Presser, Harriet and Gita Sen, Oxford University Press, New York, NY. Kishor, S. and Gupta, K. (2004), “Women’s empowerment in India and its states: evidence from the NFHS”, Economic and Political Weekly, Vol. 39 No. 7, pp. 694-712. Kishor, S. and Subaiya, L. (2008), “Understanding women’s empowerment: a comparative analysis of demographic and health surveys (DHS) data”, DHS Comparative Reports No. 20, MACRO International, Calverton, MD. Kritz, M.M., Makinwa-Adebusoye, P. and, (1999), “Determinants of women’s decision-making authority in Nigeria: the ethnic dimension”, Sociological Forum, Vol. 14 No. 3, pp. 399-424. Malhotra, A. and Mather, M. (1997), “Do schooling and work empower women in developing countries? Gender and domestic decisions in Sri Lanka”, Sociological Forum, Vol. 12 No. 4, pp. 599-630. Malhotra, A. and Schuler, S.R. (2005), “Women’s empowerment as a variable in international development”, Measuring Empowerment: Cross-Disciplinary Perspectives, pp. 71-88. Mason, K.O. (1997), How Family Position Influences Married Women’s Autonomy and Power in Five Asian Countries, East-West Center, Honolulu, HI. Mason, K. O. (1996), “Wives economic decision-making power in the family in five Asian countries”, in Mason K.O. (Ed.), the Changing Family in Comparative Perspective: Asia and the United States, East-West Center, Honolulu. Mason, K. (1998), “Wives economic decision-making power in the family in five Asian countries”, in Mason K.O. (Ed.), The Changing Family in Comparative Perspective: Asia and the United States, East-West Center, Honolulu. Mason, K.O. and Smith, H.L. (2000), “Husbands’ versus wives’ fertility goals and use of contraception: the influence of gender context in five Asian countries”, Demography, Vol. 37 No. 3, pp. 299-311. Mogford, E. (2011), “When status hurts: dimensions of women’s status and domestic abuse in rural Northern India”, Violence against Women, Vol. 17 No. 7, pp. 835-857. Namoro, S. and Roushdy, R. (2009), “Intrahousehold resource allocation in Egypt: women’s empowerment and investment in children”, Middle East Development Journal, Vol. 1 No. 1, pp. 105-121. Nawar, L., Lloyd, C.B. and Barbara, I. (1995), “Women’s autonomy and gender roles in Egyptian families”, In: Obermeyer, C.M. (Ed.), Family, Gender, and Population in the Middle East: Policies in Context, American University in Cairo Press, pp. 147-178. REPS 3,3/4 170 Oropesa, R.S. (1997), “Development and marital power in Mexico”, Social Forces, Vol. 75 No. 4, pp. 1291-1318. Parveen, S. and Leonhäuser, I.-U. (2005), Empowerment of Rural Women, in Bangladesh: A household level analysis, Vol. 72, Margraf, Berlin. Population Census (2006), Central Agency for Public Mobilization and Statistics (CAPMAS). Robert, O., Jr, Donald, M.W. and Blood, (1960), “Husbands and wives: the dynamics of married living”, Free Press,. Glencoe, Ill. Rodman, H. (1972), “Marital power and the theory of resources in cultural context”, Journal of Comparative Family Studies, Vol. 3 No. 1, pp. 50-69. Rogler, L.H., Cooney, R.S., Hurrell, R.M. and Ortiz, V. (1982), “Decision making in intergenerational puerto Rican families”, Journal of Marriage and the Family, Vol. 44 No. 3, pp. 621-631. Rose, A.K. and Spiegel, M.M. (2009), “Cross-country causes and consequences of the 2008 crisis: early warning”, Federal Reserve Bank of San Francisco, Working Paper 2009-17. Roushdy, R. (2004), “Intrahousehold resource allocation in Egypt: does women’s empowerment lead to greater investments in children?”, Economic Research Forum. Salem, R., Cheong, Y.F. and Yount, K.M. (2017), “Is women’s work a pathway to their agency in rural Minya, Egypt?”, Social Indicators Research, pp. 1-25. UNDP and Ministry of Economic Development (2010), “Egypt progress toward achieving the millennium development goals”. Upadhyay, U.D. and Karasek, D.D. (2010), “Women’s empowerment and achievement of desired fertility in sub-Saharan Africa”, DHS Working Papers No. 80. Calverton, ICF Macro, MD. Varghese, T. (2011), “Women empowerment in Oman: a study based on women empowerment index”, Far East Journal of Psychology and Business, Vol. 2, No. 2, February. Vlassoff, C. (1994), “Gender inequalities in health in the third world: uncharted ground”, Social Science and Medicine, Vol. 39 No. 9, pp. 1249-1259. Whyte, M.K. (1978), The Status of Women in Preindustrial Societies, Princeton University Press. Xu, X. and Shu-Chuan, L. (2002), “Resources, gender ideologies, and marital power: the case of Taiwan”, Journal of Family Issues, Vol. 23 No. 2, pp. 209-245. Yount, K.M. (2005), “Women’s family power and gender preference in Minya, Egypt”, Journal of Marriage and Family, Vol. 67 No. 2, pp. 410-428. Yount, K.M., VanderEnde, K.E., Dodell, S., Cheong, Y.F. and, (2015), “Measurement of women’s agency in Egypt: a national validation study”, Social Indicators Research, Vol. 128 No. 3, pp. 1171-1192. Zaman, H. (1999), “Assessing the poverty and vulnerability impact of micro-credit in Bangladesh”, A case study of BRAC, Bangladesh, pp. 2-7. Further reading Basu, A.M. and Gayatri Brij, K. (2005), “Two concepts of female empowerment: some leads from DHS data on women’s status and reproductive health”, A Focus on Gender–Collected Papers on Gender Using DHS Data, ORC Macro, Calverton MD, pp. 15-33. Central Agency for Public Mobilization and Statistics (CAPMAS) “Poverty indicators according to the egyptian integrated household survey, 2010/2011”, Deepa, Narayan-Parker, (Ed.) (2005), Measuring Empowerment: Cross-Disciplinary Perspectives, World Bank Publications, Washington DC. El-Zanaty, F.H., Hussein, A.S., Zaky, H.H. and Ann, A.W. (1993), “Egypt demographic and health survey 1992”, Macro International, Calverton, MD. Kabeer, N. (2017), “Economic pathways to women’s empowerment and active citizenship: what does the evidence from Bangladesh tell us?”, The Journal of Development Studies, Vol. 53 No. 5, pp. 649-663. Resources versus social constrains 171 Kishor, S. (1993), “‘May god give sons to all’: gender and child mortality in India”, American Sociological Review, Vol. 58 No. 2, pp. 247-265. Kishor, S. (2000b), “Women’s contraceptive use in Egypt: what do direct measures of empowerment tell us?”, “in Annual Meeting of the Population Association of America, Los Angeles, pp. 23-25. Mosedale, S. (2005), “Assessing women’s empowerment: towards a conceptual framework”, Journal of International Development, Vol. 17 No. 2, pp. 243-257. Corresponding author Hanan Nazier can be contacted at: hanan.nazier@feps.edu.eg REPS 3,3/4 172 mailto:hanan.nazier@feps.edu.eg Appendix 1 Appendix 2. The decision and mobility indicators and their answers Decision-making indicators include the following six questions: (1) DI1: Who has the final say on making large household’s purchase? (2) DI2: Who has the final say on making household’s purchase for every day? (3) DI3: Who has the final say on your own visits to family and friends? (4) DI4: Who has the final say on what food should be cooked? (5) DI5: Who has the final say on getting medical treatment for herself? (6) DI6: Who has the final say on getting clothes for herself? Each indicator may take one of the following values: � 2 if the respondent takes the decision alone. � 1 if the respondent takes the decision with someone else (husband, father, mother [. . .] etc). � 0 if she is not involved in the decision at all. For the mobility indicators, it includes the following four questions: (1) MI1: Do you need permission to go to local market? (2) MI2: Do you need permission to go to local health center? (3) MI3: Do you need permission to take children to health center? (4) MI4: Do you need permission to go to friends or relative house? Each indicator may take one of the following values: � 4 if she needs no permission � 3 if she needs to just inform them. � 2 if she need permission. � 1 if she cannot go alone. Figure A1. MIMIC Model Resources versus social constrains 173 Appendix 3 Table AI. Estimated impact of empowerment on the different indicators for mobility (MIMIC) DI1 DI2 DI3 DI4 DI5 DI6 Empowerment 1(0) 2.048***(0.116) 1.589***(0.0781) 1.693***(0.0948) 1.609***(0.0813) 1.610***(0.0825) Observations 5,222 5,222 5,222 5,222 5,222 5,222 Notes: Standard errors in parentheses; ***p < 0.01, ** p < 0.05, * p < 0.1 Table AII. Estimated impact of empowerment on the different indicators for mobility (MIMIC) MI1 MI2 MI3 MI4 Empowerment 1(0) 2.723***(0.170) 1.549***(0.0709) 1.195***(0.0541) Observations 5,222 5,222 5,222 5,222 Notes: Standard errors in parentheses; ***p < 0.01, ** p < 0.05, * p < 0.1 REPS 3,3/4 174 Appendix 4 Table AIII. Estimated coefficients of the decision-making and mobility regressions without regional dummies Decision Mobility Variables Empowerment Empowerment Social resources Respondent’s age 0.0546*** (0.0105) 0.0564*** (0.0122) Respondent’s age squared �0.000611*** (0.000157) �0.000728*** (0.000183) Father’s employment status (Reference category: unpaid family worker/no job) Wage worker 0.174** (0.0729) 0.220*** (0.0844) Employer 0.145* (0.0745) 0.211** (0.0862) Self-employed 0.157** (0.0767) 0.180** (0.0888) Mother’s employment status (Reference category: no job) Wage worker 0.0981*** (0.0375) 0.0378 (0.0432) Employer/self-employed 0.216*** (0.0740) 0.0643 (0.0848) Unpaid family worker 0.143*** (0.0445) 0.0758 (0.0512) Share of marriage cost 0.248*** (0.0563) 0.202*** (0.0646) Economic resources Respondent’s education (Reference category: Illiterate) Literate/Basic – Intermediate Education �0.0108 (0.0292) 0.0229 (0.0338) Secondary education 0.0146 (0.0291) 0.00359 (0.0336) Post-Secondary – Post University Education �0.0270 (0.0385) �0.0780* (0.0446) Respondent was employed in 2006 0.0160 (0.0226) 0.0227 (0.0261) Respondent’s wealth status (Reference Category: First quintile) Second quintile 0.0355 (0.0254) 0.0107 (0.0293) Third quintile 0.0421* (0.0239) 0.0497* (0.0277) Fourth quintile 0.0268 (0.0255) 0.00936 (0.0295) Fifth quintile 0.0479*** (0.00900) �0.0136 (0.0102) Social constraints Are you daughter in law? �0.354*** (0.0438) �0.130*** (0.0486) Do you have an adult son living with you? 0.0821** (0.0339) �0.0161 (0.0390) Number of children �0.0176** (0.00706) 0.0523*** (0.00841) Age gap between the respondent and her husband (Reference category: he is older than her) He is younger than her 0.0322 (0.0447) 0.0829 (0.0518) He has the same age as her 0.0491 (0.0495) 0.0162 (0.0573) Education gap between the respondent and her husband (Reference category: they have the same education level) He has higher education by two or more levels �0.0658* (0.0394) �0.142*** (0.0459) He has higher education by one level �0.0177 (0.0235) �0.0688** (0.0272) He has lower education by two or more levels 0.0416 (0.0490) 0.0174 (0.0568) He has lower education by one level 0.0584** (0.0265) 0.0306 (0.0306) Husband’s employment status (reference category: no job) wage worker �0.0372 (0.0364) �0.00230 (0.0418) Employer/self-employed �0.0831** (0.0391) �0.0793* (0.0450) Observations 5,222 5,222 Notes: Standard errors in parentheses; ***p < 0.01, ** p < 0.05, *p < 0.1 Resources versus social constrains 175 What empowers Egyptian women: resources versus social constrains? Introduction Background 2.1 Defining and measuring women’s empowerment and agency 2.2 Women’s empowerment measurement 2.3 Theoretical foundations of determinants of women’s economic empowerment 2.4 Empirical evidence of women’s economic empowerment in Egypt 3. Methodology 4. Data 5. Empirical results 6. Discussions and conclusion References work_km3clpwg7rhptfpnf4xt75inme ---- UAJB_A_1214333_O King’s Research Portal DOI: 10.1080/15265161.2016.1214333 Document Version Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Link to publication record in King's Research Portal Citation for published version (APA): Venkatapuram, S. (2016). Justice and Global Health Research. AMERICAN JOURNAL OF BIOETHICS, 16(10), 46-66. https://doi.org/10.1080/15265161.2016.1214333 Citing this paper Please note that where the full-text provided on King's Research Portal is the Author Accepted Manuscript or Post-Print version this may differ from the final Published version. If citing, it is advised that you check and use the publisher's definitive version for pagination, volume/issue, and date of publication details. And where the final published version is provided on the Research Portal, if citing you are again advised to check the publisher's website for any subsequent corrections. General rights Copyright and moral rights for the publications made accessible in the Research Portal are retained by the authors and/or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing publications that users recognize and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. •Users may download and print one copy of any publication from the Research Portal for the purpose of private study or research. •You may not further distribute the material or use it for any profit-making activity or commercial gain •You may freely distribute the URL identifying the publication in the Research Portal Take down policy If you believe that this document breaches copyright please contact librarypure@kcl.ac.uk providing details, and we will remove access to the work immediately and investigate your claim. Download date: 06. Apr. 2021 https://doi.org/10.1080/15265161.2016.1214333 https://kclpure.kcl.ac.uk/portal/en/publications/justice-and-global-health-research(318fbafa-682b-4e2e-807b-646a69d6dccb).html https://doi.org/10.1080/15265161.2016.1214333 Open Peer Commentaries Justice and Global Health Research Sridhar Venkatapuram, University of Johannesburg and King’s College London One of the most interesting and knotty puzzles in global health justice can be found in Margaret Whitehead’s deci- sion tree for determining which health inequalities across human beings demand a social response. Whitehead argued that the subset of health inequalities that are avoidable, unnecessary, and unfair or unjust are health “inequities” (Whitehead 1990). While inequalities are value-free observa- tions, inequities are moral bads that demand social action. While the effort is praiseworthy, I have argued elsewhere that many aspects of the health equity principles are prob- lematic (Venkatapuram 2011). In particular, at the first step, a health inequality or impairment that is deemed unavoid- able is moved outside of the scope of equity, ethics, and jus- tice. In philosophy, it is often stated that a moral “ought implies can.” So if a disease/impairment is unpreventable or untreatable, there cannot be an ethical duty to prevent or mitigate a resulting health inequality. However, such a first cut would also dissipate any claims to or duties to conduct research on a disease/impairment that is currently unavoid- able because we lack the knowledge about how to do so. A health inequality can also be unavoidable because there are not enough resources in a specific location to apply extant knowledge such as in many developing countries. Therefore, in relation to health and more, the prevailing view has been that moral claims and duties that cannot be immediately ful- filled are meaningless. Informed by his analyses of famines and Ronald Dworkin’s account of rights, Amartya Sen offered a novel argument for a “meta-right”—a meta-right to x is a right to policies p(x) that genuinely aim to have the right to x realizable (Sen 1984). Sen’s meta-right challenges Whitehead’s first principle. When a health inequality is deemed unavoidable, a meta-right to health can still moti- vate both health sciences research and broader social and economic policies that aim toward realizing a right to health. That is why it is at the core of my argument for a human right to health or, more accurately, a meta-right to the meta- capability to be healthy. It is thus noteworthy that Pratt and Hyder present a jus- tice-based argument and an “ethical checklist” for the governance of transnational global health research consortia (GHRCs) (Pratt and Hyder 2016) They present criteria for what global health research should be done as well as who should do what, where, when, how, and so forth. Impor- tantly, these criteria are said to reflect the capabilities approach (CA) to (global) health justice, particularly relying on Jennifer Prah Ruger’s prolific writings on health (care) governance. I am wholly sympathetic with the mission of linking global health research to conceptions of (global) jus- tice, as well as to extending and utilizing the CA for such a mission. However, Pratt and Hyder’s argument is unsatisfac- tory. I focus on three aspects, including their principle of LMICs first and foremost; their priority of worst off in terms of shortfall equity; and their purpose of science. Throughout the article and in the checklist, Pratt and Hyder assert the importance of the GHRCs ensuring that their LMIC research partners are the center of the research endeavor; their voices and those of their community mem- bers must be heard; their priorities should determine the GHRC’s priorities; most of the GHRC’s resources should go to the LMIC researchers and research; and leadership roles should be given to LMIC researchers. Pratt and Hyder do not provide any justification for why research resources should be directed to LMICs in the first place, or for why GHRCs should be initially formed. They point to the CA for such justification, and focus on arguing for put- ting LMIC research(ers) first in various aspects of the func- tioning of the consortia. This is understandable as so much of health equity, human rights, and human-centered devel- opment thinking argues for participation of those affected (i.e., “nothing about us without us”). However, an impor- tant consideration moves against a uniform central role for LMIC researchers, especially codified into a checklist. In global justice philosophy, there is a general acceptance of an ethical duty to correct harms one has caused even if it occurs in other countries (Føllesdal and Pogge 2005). It is also recognized that there is an ethical duty to prevent possible future harms from one’s actions. Correcting past harms and preventing future harms could address significant human Published with license by Taylor & Francis. � 2016 Sridhar Venkatapuram This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License (http://creativecommons.org/ licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is prop- erly cited. The moral rights of the named author(s) have been asserted. Address correspondence to Sridhar Venkatapuram, King’s College London, Dept SSHM, The Strand, London, WC2R 2LS, United Kingdom. E-mail: sridhar.venkatapuram@kcl.ac.uk 46 ajob The American Journal of Bioethics, 16(10): 46–66, 2016 Copyright © Taylor & Francis Group, LLC ISSN: 1526-5161 print / 1536-0075 online DOI: 10.1080/15265161.2016.1214333 suffering/health inequalities in the world. This could produce duties to conduct global health research and form GHRCs. For actors who appear to have no past or future harm links to people that are suffering in the world, the possible duty to act is based on capacity. (Sen 2009; Singer 2004) One has a moral obligation to consider helping alleviate suffering of individu- als wherever one finds them, in light of and commensurate to one’s capacity to do so. In other words, one ought to help if one can and to the extent one can. According to Pratt and Hyder’s argument, rich country GHRC members may have exceptional capacity but their focus must be on building self- sufficiency of LMIC research partners. Why should improv- ing skills and capacity of LMIC researchers be a stronger moral duty than the duty of helping alleviate suffering of peo- ple commensurate with one’s exceptional capacity? There is no central tenet of the CA that would privilege LMIC researchers in all aspects. Moreover, GHRCs usually involve LMIC researchers across a number of countries. While the authors focus on the dyadic relationships between LMIC and HIC researchers, what are the procedures and principles for adjudicating disagreements between researchers from differ- ent LMICs within the consortia? Pratt and Hyder argue that research priorities of GHRCs should reflect the needs of the worst off in LMICs. Following Ruger, they define the worst off in terms of those who have the greatest shortfall from the world’s highest/best health achievements (Ruger 2010). While it is not clear whether the basic unit is individuals or groups, let’s assume they mean groups (contra a central aspect of the CA). If we take Japan, which has the world’s highest life expectancy as the standard, then those LMICs or groups within LMICs with the greatest shortfall from that Japanese threshold should get priority in research. However, shortfall equity does not necessarily mean that the standard from which one measures has to be the highest achievable outcome in the world. A sufficient or aver- age threshold could also be used. Pratt and Hyder go with the highest outcomes in human populations. Given that there is reasonable disagreement on whether one kind of impairment is worse than other, or whether staying alive is always good, there would have to be a lot of work done before we could rank which LMICs or groups according to their shortfalls. One could imagine that a measurement such as the disability- adjusted life year (DALY) would be very helpful. It may be plausible to identify what diseases/impairments create the greatest shortfall (most DALYs lost) across countries or across groups within countries. Such ranking could then act as a research priority-setting exercise for GHRCs. However, whether using DALYs or another metric, much more reason- ing must be provided for aiming to achieve maximal out- comes. Prioritizing research according to greatest group shortfall presumably is in order to produce research outputs that will have the greatest reductions in health inequalities. Given that the CA was partially born out of the critique of utilitarianism including its central tenet of maximization, it would be inconsistent to aim for maximization in a CA-based argument without giving a clear justification. A third and important component of Pratt and Hyder’s argument is the implicit assertion that the primary aim of GHRCs should be reducing health disparities within and across countries. Given that GHRCs are research coordi- nating entities, the assertion is that the aim of the scientists involved should be to reduce health disparities. Further- more, as the checklist is meant for all GHRCs, all scientists involved in any GHRC must do science that aims to reduce health disparities (to the greatest extent). While we may be able to argue that one primary aim of GHRCs should be to reduce health disparities on various grounds, the move to assert that all the research and scientists involved in GHRCs must have a social mission may be unwise. Recon- ciling the aims and methods of scientific practice with instrumental and social goals such as reducing health dis- parities requires much more careful reasoning than pro- vided here. The authors are especially vulnerable for relying on Ruger’s expositions on governance in order to establish the moral purpose of GHRCs and their scientists. In particu- lar, the debates about the moral purposes of health sciences have recently flourished to the greatest extent in relation to social determinants of health research, or social epidemiol- ogy. At least in the articles the authors cite, Ruger expressly excludes social determinants of health from social policy because “we do not know enough.” Ruger’s argument regarding research is that the focus on health capability motivates claims to research on health care, broadly under- stood to include public health goods and services and equi- table finance. As a result, Ruger’s governance framework is closed off to important ethical arguments for doing science to reduce social inequalities in health while also doing excel- lent science. Without being informed by these debates or much philosophy of science, Pratt and Hyder’s argument and checklist are vulnerable to the charge that the health sci- ences are being infused with social values and likely to result in bad science. & REFERENCES Føllesdal, A., and T. Pogge. 2005. Real world justice: Grounds, princi- ples, human rights, and social institutions. Dordrecht, The Nether- lands: Springer. Pratt, B., and A. A. Hyder. 2016. Governance of transnational global health research consortia and health equity. American Jour- nal of Bioethics 16(10): 29–45. Ruger, J. P. 2010. Health and social justice. Oxford, UK: Oxford Uni- versity Press. Sen, A. 1984. The right not to be hungry. In The right to food, ed. P. Alston and K. Tomasevski, 69–81. Dordrecht, the Netherlands: The Netherlands Human Rights Centre. Sen, A. 2009. The idea of justice. London, UK: Allen Lane. Singer, P. 2004. One world: The ethics of globalization, 2nd ed. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Venkatapuram, S. 2011. Health justice. An argument from the capabili- ties approach. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press . Whitehead, M. 1990. The concepts and principles of equity in health, 29. Copenhagen, Denmark: World Health Organization Regional Office for Europe. Transnational Global Health Research Consortia October, Volume 16, Number 10, 2016 ajob 47 work_ksbqlz3spnakdmx22k74pll7jm ---- ACCESS TO JUSTICE: PURSUIT OF A NOBLE PURPOSE (Schedule subject to change 5-8-13) AND JUSTICE FOR ALL? William S. Richardson School of Law University of Hawaii Friday, June 21, 2013 8:00 - 8:30 a.m. Continental breakfast; registration 8:30 Dean Aviam Soifer and Robert LeClair, co-emcees 8:35 - 8:55 Hon. Mark E. Recktenwald, Chief Justice, Hawaii Supreme Court 8:55 - 9:15 A Commissioner’s Perspective A moderated discussion of current commissioners of the Hawaii Access to Justice Commission who are members of the Hawaii Consortium of Legal Services Providers. Panel: Nalani Fujimori Kaina, L. Dew Kaneshiro, Nanci Kriedman 9:15 - 10:15 “Unconscious Bias:” What It Is and What Its Ramifications Are On Equal Justice for All? Charles R. Lawrence, III, Centennial Professor, William S. Richardson School of Law, University of Hawaii at Manoa 10:15 - 10:30 Break 10:30 - 11:30 Where Is the Money? (Funding challenges for access to justice) Legislative Panel (Moderator: Dean Aviam Soifer) 11:35 - 12:35 Light lunch 12:45 - 2:00 Concurrent Workshops I: 1. Restorative Justice in Civil Cases This session will explore the basic concepts of restorative justice in the civil arena and plan of action. Panel: Susan Serrano, Lorenn Walker 2. Micronesians and Access to Justice This session will examine the issues facing Micronesian immigrants to Hawaii, the obstacles to equal justice, including language and cultural barriers, and plan of action. Panel: Jocelyn Howard, Joakim Peter, Dina Shek 3. “Outside the Box” Thinking: Using Technology and Other Strategies This session will explore strategies for access to justice for the underserved, including how to sell pro bono to volunteer attorneys, how to develop provocative changes, how to help. Panel: Judge Donald Horowitz (ret.), David Reber 4. Access to Justice in the Family Court This session will examine the hot access to justice issues in Family Court and plan of action. Panel: Judge R. Mark Browning, Judge Catherine Remigio, Thomas Crowley 2:00 - 2:15 Break 2:15 - 3:30 Concurrent Workshops II: 5. Delivery of Legal Services through Limited Scope Representation This session will describe the concepts of limited scope representation, ethical standards, and plan of action. Panel: Judge Barbara Richardson, Judge Trudy Senda 6. Mediation Effectiveness: When to Use It and How to Make It Work This session will explore the nuances of mediation and its effectiveness and plan of action. Panel: Judge Joel August (ret.), Judge Ronald Ibarra, Chuck Crumpton 7. Language Access and Your Clients This session will cover issues that commonly arise where clients have limited English proficiency, including client interviewing techniques, how to locate and work with an interpreter, effective solutions, and plan of action. Panel: Justice Sabrina S. McKenna, Christine Kubota, Steven Silver 8. Responses to the Legal Problems Faced by Veterans This session will examine the problems concerning evictions, public housing, homelessness, other hot topics related to the underserved veterans and plan of action. Panel: Judge Edward Kubo, Colin Kippen, Pamela Harms 3:30 - 4:15 Looking to the Future for Justice for All Panel: Hon. Mark E. Recktenwald, Hon. Simeon R. Acoba, Hon. Daniel R. Foley, Jill Hasegawa; (Moderator: Robert LeClair) “Hawai`i Pono`i” (Schedule subject to change 5-8-13) AND JUSTICE FOR ALL? William S. Richardson School of Law University of Hawaii Friday, June 21, 2013 work_ktbaecn7n5aoldzymert3plyme ---- None work_kyxfkcobang3rhfm6lbwnz6pme ---- Real World Justice Real World Justice Author(s): Thomas Pogge Reviewed work(s): Source: The Journal of Ethics, Vol. 9, No. 1/2, Current Debates in Global Justice (2005), pp. 29-53 Published by: Springer Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/25115814 . Accessed: 25/07/2012 10:00 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. . Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Ethics. http://www.jstor.org http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=springer http://www.jstor.org/stable/25115814?origin=JSTOR-pdf http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp THOMAS POGGE REAL WORLD JUSTICE (Received 14 May 2004; accepted in revised form 3 June 2004) ABSTRACT. Despite a high and growing global average income, billions of human beings are still condemned to lifelong severe poverty with all its attendant evils of low life expectancy, social exclusion, ill health, illiteracy, dependency, and effective enslavement. We citizens of the rich countries are conditioned to think of this problem as an occasion for assistance. Thanks in part to the rationalizations dispensed by our economists, most of us do not realize how deeply we are implicated, through the new global economic order our states have imposed, in this ongoing catastrophe. My sketch of how we are so implicated follows the argument of my book, World Poverty and Human Rights, but takes the form of a response to the book's critics. KEY WORDS: causal explanation, development economics, global resources dividend, harm, human rights, inequality, justice, negative duties, world poverty, WTO Can normative theories about global justice benefit from empirical theories? This is a rhetorical question - no one seriously argues that we should think about global justice in ignorance of the facts. And the question is also a bit tendentious, prodding us philosophers (heads in the clouds or buried in sand) to pay more attention to the real world as presented, most relevantly, by development econo mists. I agree that many philosophers working on global justice know too little about the real world, but I also believe that we should absorb the theories delivered by economists with a great deal of caution. A prominent concept in economics is that of homo eco nomicus, an individual who, single-mindedly and rationally, seeks optimally to satisfy his preferences. Such imaginary creatures are not good approximations of persons in the real world. But, as various studies have shown, they do approximate pretty well the kind of people we find in business schools and economics depart ments - people who cannot comprehend how it could possibly make sense to tip a waiter in a place one does not intend to revisit. The Journal of Ethics (2005) 9: 29-53 ? Springer 2005 30 THOMAS POGGE Insofar as they approximate the ideal type homo economicus, the work economists do - what they study and how they study it - will be driven by their career goals. These goals will rarely be served by propagating falsehoods and fallacies. But they will be served by propagating truths that are supportive, in preference to truths that are subversive, of the position and policies of those in power. While economists like to present themselves as disinterested scientists, they function today more typically as ideologists for our political and economic "elites" - much like most theologians did in an earlier age. For a nice illustration of this, just look at The Economist (March 11, 2004), which gives rather absurd arguments for the claims that global inequality is not increasing and that, in any case, global inequality and poverty are "not a question of justice." Or look at the work of development economists, from Amartya Sen to the Chicago School, which is overwhelmingly focused on relating the persistence of severe poverty to local causes - bad governance, sexist culture, geography, and much else - while leaving unstudied the huge impact of the global economic order on the incidence of poverty worldwide. Unfortu nately, in this domain we cannot just learn and benefit from the theories of the experts. We must think for ourselves and, as best we can, become experts. With this preamble, let me proceed to lay out the empirically informed view on global justice I have been defending. In an attempt to render this exercise interesting to those familiar with my work, I present my view in the form of a response to some of its critics. 1. The Central Claim In a recent book,1 I have claimed that we - the more advantaged citizens of the affluent countries - are actively responsible for most of the life-threatening poverty in the world. The book focuses on the 15 years since the end of the Cold War. In this period, billions of people have suffered greatly from poverty-related causes: from hunger and malnutrition, from child labor and trafficking, from lack of access to basic health care and safe drinking water, from lack of 1 Thomas W. Pogge, World Poverty and Human Rights: Cosmopolitan Responsi bilities and Reforms (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2002). REAL WORLD JUSTICE 31 shelter, basic sanitation, electricity, and elementary education.2 Some 18 million people have died prematurely each year from poverty-related causes, accounting for fully one third of all human deaths. This 15-year death toll of 270 million is considerably larger than the 200-million death toll from all the wars, civil wars, geno cides and other government repression of the entire 20th century combined.3 2 Among 6133 million human beings (2001), about 799 million are undernour ished [UNDP, Human Development Report 2003 (New York: Oxford University Press, 2003), p. 87]; 880 million have no access to basic medical care [UNDP, Human Development Report 1999 (New York: Oxford University Press, 1999), p. 22]; 1000 million lack access to safe drinking water (UNDP, Human Development Report 2003, p. 9); 1000 million lack adequate shelter and 2000 million have no electricity [UNDP Human Development Report 1998 (New York, Oxford University Press, 1998), p. 49]; 2400 million lack basic sanitation (UNDP: Human Development Report 2003, p. 9); and 876 million adults are illiterate (UNDP, Human Development Report 2003, p. 6). Some 250 million children (aged 5-14) do wage work outside their family, 8.4 million of them in the "unconditionally worst" forms of child labor, "defined as slavery, trafficking, debt bondage and other forms of forced labor, forced recruitment of children for use in armed conflict, prostitution and pornography, and illicit activities" [International Labour Organisation, A Future without Child Labour (Geneva: International Labor Office, 2002, www.ilo.org/public/english/standards/ decl/publ/reports/report3.htm)]. Females and people of color are heavily overrep resented in all these horrifying statistics (UNDP, Human Development Report 2003, pp. 310-330). 3 This includes World War Two (1939-45: 50 million), repression and misman agement under Mao (1949-75: 46 million), Stalin's repression (1924-53: 20 million), World War One (1914-18: 16 million), the Russian Civil War (1917-22: 9 million), the devastation visited on Congo Free State (1886-1908: 5 million), the post-war expulsion of Germans from Eastern Europe (1945-47: 3 million), KMT repression (1928-37: 3 million), the Korean War (1950-53: 2.8 million), the Vietnam War (1960-75: 2.5 million), North Korean repression (since 1948: 2 million), the Biafra/ Nigeria civil war (1966-70: 2 million), Pakistani repression in Bangla Desh (1971: 2 million), the Cambodia genocide (1975-78: 1.6 million), the civil war in the Sudan (since 1983: 1.5 million), the recent wars in the Congo (since 1998: 1.5 million), the Afghan wars (1979-2001: 1.4 million), the wars and civil wars in Rwanda and Burundi (1959-95: 1.2 million), the Armenian Genocide (1915-23: 1 million), the Mexican Revolution (1910-20: 1 million), the sanctions against Iraq (1990-2003: 1 million), the civil wars in Somalia (since 1991: 1 million), the Iran/Iraq war (1980 88: 0.9m), the partition of India (1947: 0.5 million), Suharto's coup in Indonesia (1965-66: 0.5 million), the civil war in Angola (1975-95: 0.5 million) and 259 other mega-death events of violence and repression. See http://users.erols.com/mwhite28/ war-1900.htm for the figures and the relevant literature supporting them. 32 THOMAS POGGE Some critics maintain that these problems are peanuts compared to the bad old days when a large majority of humankind was poor.4 In 1820, they tell us, 75% of humankind were living below the World Bank's "SI/day" poverty line, while today this percentage is only 20%. (This poverty line is defined in terms of the purchasing power that a monthly income of $32.74 had in the year 1993.5 In 2004, this line corresponds to the purchasing power of $500 per year in the United States.6) According to these critics, what is remarkable about world poverty is how very little of it there still is today. I disagree. For one thing, it is quite inappropriate to use per centages for the comparison. The killing of a given number of people does not become morally less troubling the more world population increases. What matters morally is the number of people in extreme poverty. In 1820, this number was about 750 million (75% of about one billion).7 In 1998, this number was nearly 1200 million.8 Since 1820, the number of extremely poor people has thus increased by over 50%, while the number of people living below the World Bank's more reasonable "$2/day" poverty line has tripled.9 Moreover, severe poverty was quite hard to avoid in 1820, because even the average purchasing power of incomes worldwide barely reached the World Bank's higher poverty line. Today, by contrast, the average pur chasing power of incomes worldwide is well over 10 times that level, and severe poverty is entirely avoidable. We are not avoiding it only because of the fantastic increase in inequality.10 4 Notably Gerald Gaus, "Radio Interview on Pogge's World Poverty and Human Rights" on Ideas and Issues (WETS-FM), 19 January 2003 (www.etsu.edu/philos/ radio/gaus-wphr.htm); and Mathias Risse, "Do We Harm the Global Poor?," pre sentation at Author Meets Critics session at the Eastern Division Meeting of the American Philosophical Association, 30 December 2003 (http://ksghome. harvard.edu/~.mrisse.academic.ksg/papers_Philosophy.htm). 5 Shaohua Chen and Martin Ravallion: "How Did the World's Poorest Fare in the 1990s?," Review of Income and Wealth 47 (2001), p. 285. 6 See www.bls.gov/cpi/home.htm. 7 See www.census.gov/ipc/www/worldhis.html. 8 Chen and Ravallion: "How Did the World's Poorest Fare in the 1990s?" p. 290; cf. www.worldbank.org/research/povmonitor for later figures. 9 To 2812 million (Chen and Ravallion, "How Did the World's Poorest Fare in the 1990s?," p. 290); see www.worldbank.org/research/povmonitor. 10 The ratio in average income between the fifth of the world's people living in the highest-income countries and the fifth living in the lowest income countries "was 74 REAL WORLD JUSTICE 33 My main claim is then that, by shaping and enforcing the social conditions that foreseeably and avoidably cause the monumental suffering of global poverty, we are harming the global poor - or, to put it more descriptively, we are active participants in the largest, though not the gravest, crime against humanity ever committed. Adolf Hitler and Joseph Stalin were vastly more evil than our political leaders, but in terms of killing and harming people they never came anywhere near causing 18 million deaths per year. Most of my readers believe that this claim is obviously mistaken, if not preposterous. Perhaps for this reason, they pay little attention to the structure and details of the case I am building. Instead, they present various general conjectures about what my mistake may be. They suggest that I am making conceptual mistakes by re-labeling as harm what are really failures to aid and protect.11 They suggest that I am factually wrong about the causal explanation of severe poverty or confused about the counterfactuals to which I compare the world as it is.12 They suggest that I am morally wrong by presenting as min imal certain moral requirements that are actually excessively demanding.13 These criticisms are worth addressing, and I will to 1 in 1997, up from 60 to 1 in 1990 and 30 to 1 in 1960. [Earlier] the income gap between the top and bottom countries increased from 3 to 1 in 1820 to 7 to 1 in 1870 to 11 to 1 in 1913" (UNDP: Human Development Report 1999, p. 3; see also p. 38). The trend is no more encouraging when one compares the incomes of households worldwide via purchasing power parities: Over a recent five-year period, "world inequality has increased ... from a Gini of 62.8 in 1988 to 66.0 in 1993. This rep resents an increase of 0.6 Gini points per year. This is a very fast increase, faster than the increase experienced by the United States and United Kingdom in the decade of the 1980's. ... The bottom 5% of the world grew poorer, as their real incomes decreased between 1988 and 1993 by 25%, while the richest quintile grew richer. It gained 12% in real terms, that is it grew more than twice as much as mean world income (5.7%)" [Branko Milanovic, "True World Income Distribution, 1988 and 1993: First Calculation Based on Household Surveys Alone," The Economic Journal 112 (2002), p. 88, see www.blackwellpublishers.co.uk/specialarticles/ecoj50673 pdf]. 11 Gaus: "Radio Interview on Pogge's World Poverty and Human Rights;" Alan Patten, "Remarks on Pogge's World Poverty and Human Rights" at Author Meets Critics session at the Eastern Division Meeting of the American Philosophical Association, 30 December 2003. 12 Gaus, "Radio Interview on Pogge's World Poverty and Human Rights"; Debra Satz, "Comments on Pogge's World Poverty and Human Rights" at Author Meets Critics session at the Eastern Division Meeting of the American Philosophical Association, 30 December 2003. 13 Patten, "Remarks on Pogge's World Poverty and Human Rights" 34 THOMAS POGGE address many of them in the context of explaining the main lines of argument in the book. 2. Positive Duties Before doing this, I should dispose of one misunderstanding. My book seeks to show how existing world poverty manifests a violation of our negative duties, our duties not to harm. To show this, I leave positive duties aside. I do not assert that there are no positive duties, or that such duties are feeble. Rather, I avoid claims about positive duties so as to make clear that my case does not depend on such claims. My focus is solely on duties not to harm as well as on duties to avert harms that one's own past conduct may cause in the future. Duties of this last kind - to avert harms that one's past conduct may cause in the future - do not fit well into the conventional dichotomy of positive and negative duties. They are positive insofar as they require the agent to do something and also negative insofar as this requirement is continuous with the duty to avoid causing harm to others. One might call them intermediate duties, in recognition also of their intermediate stringency. My focus is exclusively on negative and intermediate duties, and thus on harm we are materially involved in causing rather than on all the harm people suffer. This focus is motivated by the belief that negative and interme diate moral duties are more stringent than positive ones. For exam ple, the duty not to assault people is more stringent than the duty to prevent such assaults by others. And, having assaulted another, the attacker has more reason to ensure that his victim's injuries are treated than a bystander would. Suggesting these views in the book, I do assume something about positive duties after all. But this is meant to be a very weak assumption, accepted not merely by libertarians but by pretty much all, except act-consequentialists. I do not assume that any negative or intermediate duty is more stringent than all positive duties. Rather, I assume that negative and intermediate duties are more stringent than positive duties when what is at stake for all concerned is held constant}4 I go to some length to stress that I do not believe the absurdity some critics15 have attributed to me: namely that any negative duty, including the duty to refrain from doing some 14 Pogge, World Poverty and Human Rights, p. 132. 15Notably Satz, "Comments on Pogge's World Poverty and Human Rights" REAL WORLD JUSTICE 3 5 small harm, is more stringent than every positive duty, including the duty to rescue thousands of children.16 Now if negative duties (not to harm) and intermediate duties (to avert harms that one's past conduct may cause in the future) are indeed more stringent than positive duties, then it could be mis leading to appeal only to positive duties when duties of the other two kinds are also in play. Consider a corporation polluting a river with dire consequences for the health of many. One might ask this cor poration, along with other businesses in the region, to help reduce that problem through donations toward purchasing pollution control equipment and toward paying for medical treatment of those sick ened by the pollution. This sort of request may be politically opportune. But it also misleadingly suggests that the polluting cor poration is morally in the same boat as the other potential donors: helping out for a good cause, pursuant to an imperfect positive duty of occasional charity. In fact, these two points are related. What makes such a plea in the positive-duty idiom politically opportune (when it is so) typically is precisely the misleading suggestion that its addressees have no negative and intermediate duties to forestall the harm they are being asked to help mitigate. One may well think that being misleading is a very small price to pay for political success against the catastrophic problem of world poverty. But, for better or worse, it does not seem that we are actually facing this choice. The appeal to positive duties has been well pre sented by Peter Singer, Henry Shue, Peter Unger, and others.17 If citizens in the affluent countries were minimally decent and humane, they would respond to these appeals and would do their bit to eradicate world poverty. If they did this, my argument would be of much less interest and importance, and I might not see the need to elaborate it at such length. As it is, I see it as my best chance to 16 I repeatedly warn against this misunderstanding in formulations such as this: "I hope I have made clear enough that this is not presented as a strict, or lexical, hierarchy: It is generally acknowledged that a higher moral reason can be out weighed by a lower, if more is at stake in the latter" (Pogge, World Poverty and Human Rights, p. 240, note 207; see also p. 132 and p. 241, note 216). 17 Peter Singer, "Famine, Affluence and Morality," Philosophy and Public Affairs 1 (1972), pp. 229-243; Henry Shue, Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence, and U.S. Foreign Policy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1980); and Peter Unger, Living High and Letting Die: Our Illusion of Innocence (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1999). 36 THOMAS POGGE contribute to ending or reducing the immense deprivations we affluent are now inflicting upon the global poor. I also see my argument as essential to an accurate portrayal of how we affluent citizens of the rich countries are morally related to those deprivations. Yes, we are able to alleviate them, and, seeing how cheaply this can be done, we surely have positive duties to do so. But because we are also implicated, with many others, in shaping and enforcing the social institutions that produce these deprivations, and are moreover benefiting from the enormous inequalities these unjust institutions reproduce, we have much more stringent duties to seek to reform these social institutions and to do our fair share toward mitigating the harms they cause. 3. An Ecumenical Approach to Demonstrating Harm Let us now look at the arguments of the book. The case I seek to build is broadly ecumenical. I am trying to convince not merely the adherents of some particular moral conception or theory - Lockeans or Rawlsians or libertarians or communitarians, for example. Rather, I am trying to convince the adherents of all the main views now alive in Western political thought. This ambition makes the task much harder, because I must defend my conclusion on multiple fronts, fielding parallel arguments that address and appeal to diverse and often mutually incompatible moral conceptions and beliefs. This ecumenical strategy has been confusing to some who com plain that I am unclear and inconsistent about the baseline relative to which the global poor are supposedly harmed by existing institutional arrangements.18 They are right that I do not provide a single con sistent such baseline. But they are wrong to see this as a flaw. If I want to convince readers with diverse ideas about morality and jus tice, then I must support my conclusions with diverse arguments. And these may have to appeal to diverse baselines. A state-of-nature baseline is relevant to a reader with Lockean or Nozickian views. But a Rawlsian will reject such a baseline, insisting that the existing dis tributional profile should be compared to the profiles achievable under alternative feasible institutional arrangements. To satisfy 18 Notably Satz, "Comments on Pogge's World Poverty and Human Rights," and Patten, "Remarks on Pogge's World Poverty and Human Rights." REAL WORLD JUSTICE 37 readers of both kinds, I need to give different arguments to them, each with a different baseline. This is more work, to be sure. But the pay-off is that my case cannot justifiably be dismissed as dependent on some partisan moral premises or theory which readers may feel free to reject. The ecumenical strategy is broadest and most explicit in the final chapter, which argues for a global resources dividend (GRD). My first step there is to show that our world is pervaded by what, following Tom Nagel,19 I call "radical inequality": (1) The worse-off are very badly off in absolute terms. (2) They are also very badly off in relative terms - very much worse off than many others. (3) The inequality is impervious: It is difficult or impossible for the worse-off substantially to improve their lot; and most of the better-off never experience life at the bottom for even a few months and have no vivid idea of what it is like to live in that way. (4) The inequality is pervasive: It concerns not merely some aspects of life, such as the climate or access to natural beauty or high culture, but most aspects or all. (5) The inequality is avoidable: The better-off can improve the cir cumstances of the worse-off without becoming badly off them selves. I go on to assume that most of my readers demand more than the fact of radical inequality between us and the global poor as proof that we are harming them. I also assume that different readers differ on the question of what is missing. To satisfy more readers, I present in parallel three second steps of the argument, each of which shows in a different way that the existing radical inequality involves us in harming the global poor. All three strands of the argument lead to the conclusion that today's massive and severe poverty manifests a vio lation by the affluent of their negative duties: an immense crime in which we affluent citizens of the rich countries (as well as the political and economic "elites" of most poor countries) are implicated. 19 Thomas Nagel, "Poverty and Food: Why Charity Is Not Enough," in Peter Brown and Henry Shue (eds.), Food Policy: The Responsibility of the United States in the Life and Death Choices (New York: The Free Press, 1977). 38 THOMAS POGGE 4. Engaging Historical Conceptions of Social Justice In one strand of the argument I invoke the effects of a common and violent history. The present world is characterized not only by radical inequality as defined, but also by the fact that "the social starting positions of the worse-off and the better-off have emerged from a single historical process that was pervaded by massive grievous wrongs."20 I invoke these historical facts specifically for readers who believe that it matters morally how radical inequality has evolved. Most of the existing international inequality in standards of living was built up in the colonial period when today's affluent countries ruled today's poor regions of the world: trading their people like cattle, destroying their political institutions and cultures, and taking their natural resources. In 1960, when the colonizers finally left, taking what they could and destroying much else, the inequality in per capita income between Europe and Africa had grown to 30:1, and vast inequalities existed also in education, health-care, infrastructure, and legal and political organization. These inequalities greatly dis advantaged Africans in their dealings with governments and corpo rations of the affluent countries. This disadvantage helps explain why the Europe/Africa inequality in per capita income has since risen to 40:1. But even if per capita income had, since 1960, increased a full percentage point more each year in Africa than in Europe, this inequality would still be 20:1 today and would be fully erased only early in the 24th century. Readers attracted to historical-entitlement conceptions of justice disagree about the conditions an historical process must meet in order for it to justify gross inequalities in life chances. On this point, I can once more afford to be ecumenical. The relevant historical crimes were so horrendous, so diverse, and so consequential that no his torical-entitlement conception could credibly support the conclusion that our common history was sufficiently benign to justify even the radical inequalities in starting positions we are witnessing today. In short, then, upholding a radical inequality counts as harming the worse-off when the historical path on which this inequality arose is pervaded by grievous wrongs. "A morally deeply tarnished history must not be allowed to result in radical inequality."21 This is the moral rationale behind Abraham Lincoln's 40-acres-and-a-mule 20 Pogge, World Poverty and Human Rights, p. 203. 21 Pogge, World Poverty and Human Rights, p. 203. real world justice 39 promise of 1863, which of course was quickly rescinded. And it is the rationale for saying that we are not entitled to the huge advantages we enjoy from birth over the global poor, given how these inequalities have been built up. Some critics may seem to address this strand of the argument when they point out that the radical inequality between Europe and Africa might have come about even without colonialism.22 Perhaps Europe could have "taken-off ' even without slavery and stolen raw materials, and perhaps the resulting inequality would then have been equally great. In the absence of conclusive proof that, without the horrors of European conquest, severe poverty worldwide would be substantially less today, Risse suggests, we are entitled to keep and defend what we possess, even at the cost of millions of deaths each year (I wonder if he would make the same argument against the 40 acres-and-a-mule proposal). As a response to the first strand of the argument, this complaint is irrelevant. The first strand addresses readers who believe that the actual history is relevant. These readers will say: "Yes, if things had transpired as in Risse's hypothetical, then the citizens of the affluent countries might not, by upholding the radical inequality, be harming the global poor. But this has no bearing on whether such upholding of radical inequality constitutes harm in the actual world with its actual history." Still, Risse's complaint resonates with other readers who believe that it is permissible to uphold an economic distribution if merely it could have come about on a morally acceptable path. It is such readers that the second strand of my argument addresses. To be sure, any distribution, however skewed, could have been the outcome of a sequence of voluntary bets or gambles. Appeal to such a fictional history would "justify" anything and would thus be wholly implau sible. John Locke does much better, holding that a fictional history can justify the status quo only if the changes in holdings and social rules it involves are ones that all participants could have rationally agreed to. He also holds that in a state of nature persons would be entitled to a proportional share of the world's natural resources. He thus makes the justice of any institutional order depend on whether 22 Notably Risse, "Do We Harm the Global Poor?" 40 THOMAS POGGE the worst-off under it are at least as well off as people would be in a Lockean state of nature with a proportional resource share.23 Locke held, implausibly, that this condition was fulfilled in his time, claiming that "a King of a large fruitful territory [in the Americas] feeds, lodges, and is clad worse than a day Laborer in England."24 I argue that this condition is not fulfilled for the global poor today who, living below even the day laborers in Locke's England, are coercively denied "enough and as good"25 of the world's natural resources without having access to an equivalent substitute. Readers inclined to a Lockean conception disagree about the rel evant state-of-nature baseline that determines how bad the worst so cial starting positions imposed by a just social order may be. On this question I can once more be ecumenical. However one may want to imagine a state of nature among human beings on this planet, one could not realistically conceive it as producing an enduring poverty death toll of 18 million annually. Only a thoroughly organized state of civilization can sustain horrendous suffering on such a massive scale. Catering to Lockeans, the second strand of my argument invokes the uncompensated exclusion of the worse-off from a proportional share of global resources: The present world is characterized not merely by radical inequality as defined, but also by the fact that "the better-off enjoy significant advantages in the use of a single natural resource base from whose benefits the worse-off are largely, and without compensation, excluded."26 The better-off- we - are harming the worse-off insofar as the radical inequality we uphold excludes the global poor from a proportional share of the world's natural resources and any equivalent substitute. The point I was making about Locke is quite similar to one Debra Satz puts forth in a tone of criticism. For Locke, she says, "property rights, however acquired, do not prevail in the face of desperate need" because "everyone has an original pre-appropria tion claim-right to an adequate subsistence from the resources of the world."27 This is correct, although the poor can really have a 23 See Pogge, World Poverty and Human Rights, pp. 16, 137-139, and 202-203, for a fuller reading of Locke's argument. 24John Locke, "An Essay Concerning the True Original, Extent, and End of Civil Government" [1689], in Peter Laslett (ed.), John Locke: Two Treatises of Government (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1960), ?41, see ?37. 25 Locke, Two Treatises of Government, ?27, ?33. 26 Pogge, World Poverty and Human Rights, p. 202. 27 Satz, "Comments on Pogge's World Poverty and Human Rights" p. 16. REAL WORLD JUSTICE 41 claim only to a proportional resources share, not to adequate subsistence, because there may simply not be enough to go around. But why does Satz speak in this context of a "positive 'property right' of the needy in the means of subsistence"?28 What are po sitive as opposed to negative property rights? Does Satz want to say that we affluent have merely a positive duty toward the needy? This would suggest that our property rights do prevail after all - that our assets are ours though we ought to give away some. But Satz correctly presents Locke as rejecting this picture: We affluent have no rights to property, however acquired, in the face of the excluded. Rather, they have a right to what we hold. When we prevent them from exercising this right - when we deprive them of what is justly theirs - then we violate this original right of the poor and we harm them. In this way it is a violation of a negative duty to deprive others of "enough and as good" - either through unilateral appropriations or through institutional arrangements such as a radically inegalitarian property regime.29 Let me sum up the first two strands of the argument. These strands address readers for whom the justice of the present eco nomic distribution or of present economic arrangements turns on their actual or imaginable history. I conclude that such conceptions of justice cannot justify the status quo. One may try to justify the coercively upheld radical inequality today by appeal to the his torical process that actually led up to it. But this appeal fails because the actual historical process is massively pervaded by the most grievous wrongs. Alternatively, one may try to justify this coercively upheld radical inequality by appeal to some morally acceptable fictional historical process that might have led to it. On Locke's permissive version of this account, some small elite may appropriate all, or almost all, of the huge cooperative surplus produced by modern social organization. But such an elite must not enlarge its share even further by reducing the poor below the state-of-nature baseline so that this elite's share of the cooperative surplus is actually more than 100% and the share of the poor correspondingly less than zero. As it is, the citizens and govern ments of the affluent states are violating this negative duty when 28 Satz, "Comments on Pogge's World Poverty and Human Rights" p. 16. 29 This is argued at length in Pogge, World Poverty and Human Rights, Chapter 5. 42 THOMAS POGGE we, in collaboration with the ruling cliques of many poor coun tries, coercively exclude the global poor from a proportional resource share and any equivalent substitute. 5. Engaging Broadly Consequentialist Conceptions of Social Justice Most contemporary theorists of justice endorse neither of these his torical views. Instead, they hold that an economic order and the economic distribution it shapes should be assessed by its foreseeable effects against the background of its feasible alternatives. Thus Rawls considers a domestic economic order to be just if it produces fair equality of opportunity across social classes and no feasible alter native to it would afford better prospects to the least advantaged. The third strand of my argument addresses such broadly conse quentialist conceptions which invoke the effects of shared social institutions. The present world is characterized not only by radical inequality as defined, but also by the following facts: There is a shared institutional order that is shaped by the better-off and imposed on the worse-off. This institutional order is implicated in the reproduction of radical inequality in that there is a feasible institutional alternative under which so severe and extensive poverty would not persist. The radical inequality cannot be traced to extra-social factors (such as genetic handicaps or natural disasters) which, as such, affect different human beings differentially.30 When these further facts obtain, so I claim, then the better-off - we - are harming the worse-off insofar as we are upholding a shared institutional order that is unjust by foreseeably and avoidably (re)producing radical inequality. Now there are many different such broadly consequentialist con ceptions of justice which judge an institutional order by comparing its distributional effects to those its feasible alternatives would have. These conceptions differ along three dimensions. They differ in how they characterize the relevant affected parties (groups, persons, time slices of persons, etc.). They differ about the metric for assessing relevant effects (social primary goods, capabilities, welfare, etc.). And they differ about how to aggregate relevant effects across affected parties. Once again, my response to such diversity is ecumenical. I am trying to specify very minimal conditions of justice that are widely 30 Pogge, World Poverty and Human Rights, p. 199. REAL WORLD JUSTICE 43 accepted. Most broadly consequentialist theorists agree that a na tional economic order is unjust when it leaves social and economic human rights unfulfilled on a massive scale even while there is a feasible alternative order under which these human rights would be much better realized. Most theorists would demand more, of course. But I need no more for my purpose, because our global economic order does not even meet the very weak requirements that form the common core of the various broadly consequentialist theories of economic justice defended today. Keeping in mind this background as well as the remarks on positive duties in Section 2, we can now address various misreadings of my account of human rights. I understand human rights, within the context of broadly consequentialist conceptions of justice, primarily as weighty moral claims on social institutions. An institutional order is human-rights violating when it foreseeably gives rise to greater insecurity in access to the objects of human rights (physical integrity, freedom of movement, adequate nutrition, etc.) than would be rea sonably avoidable through an alternative feasible institutional design. Moral claims on social institutions are also, indirectly, moral claims against those who participate in designing and upholding these social institutions: Such agents, too, are violating human rights by imposing an institutional order under which access to the objects of human rights is foreseeably and avoidably insecure for some or all partici pants. I hold that most of the avoidable global underfulfillment of human rights today can be traced back to the design of the global institutional order: Had the avoidance of severe poverty been a pri ority in the redesign this order has undergone in the early 1990's, then most of that current global underfulfillment of human rights could have been averted. Can an individual or collective agent violate human rights directly, for example through torture - irrespective of whether there is an institutional order and, if so, of whether this order is just or unjust? I have been reluctant to answer this question affirmatively because I believe that the common use of the expression "human rights" is restricted to crimes that are in some sense official in character. I have been criticized for this reluctance on the ground that it is surely no worse to participate in the imposition of an institutional scheme under which people get tor tured than to torture people directly (holding constant what is at stake for the agents and their victims). I completely agree with this substantive point. My reluctance was based not on any 44 THOMAS POGGE comparative moral judgment, but on common usage. Still, I do not object to calling ordinary crimes of torture, rape, etc., human rights violations. In any case, this terminological issue is irrelevant to my work, which is focused specifically on human rights viola tions committed by means of imposing institutional arrangements that foreseeably produce greater serious insecurity in access to the objects of human rights than would be reasonably avoidable. Can an individual or collective agent violate human rights pas sively, by failing to protect people threatened by violence or starva tion even when this could be done safely, easily, and at low cost? Human rights are in principle enforceable, so the answer can be af firmative only in cases where it is morally permissible for some other agent to use some coercive means to force the relevant individual or collective to protect the people under threat. In addition, the right to be protected must be general and important enough to qualify as (part of) a human right. Finally, there are two terminological issues to consider. As pointed out, I have been reluctant to apply the lan guage of human rights to ordinary crimes such as a private citizen's refusal to toss a life preserver to a drowning swimmer. Moreover, with regard to passive failures to protect that are official in character, I have proposed that we classify them as official disrespect for human rights, but not as human rights violations, in order to recognize the moral significance of the passive/active distinction. I adduce three reasons in support of my plea. One is common usage. The notion of a human rights violation has an active ring and is thus not a fitting label for someone's failure to protect others when she had no role in causing their urgent need for such protection. It might seem desirable to stretch common usage so as to include certain failures to protect under this notion. But such a move might well be counterproductive with respect to that large number of human beings who - though they know about hunger and torture abroad and do not doubt that, with a bit of research, they could contribute to an effective protection effort - never do anything toward protecting foreigners in great distress. Moreover, in the world as it is, we can make a more forceful appeal to these people without stretching language. Conceding that they are not human rights violators for passively ignoring even the most vital needs of others, we can still point out that nearly all of them are human rights violators through their uncompensated participation in the imposition of a global institutional order that, foreseeably and REAL WORLD JUSTICE 45 avoidably, reproduces a huge excess in human rights underfulfill ment. In our world, most of the avoidable underfulfillment of human rights would be avoided if the global institutional order imposed by the affluent countries (in collaboration with many political elites in the developing world) were not so grievously unjust. It is hard to deny that reasonably privileged citizens of the rich democracies share some responsibility for the global institutional order which their governments are shaping and upholding. But one can question whether this order is human-rights violating. If it is not, then participation in its imposition cannot constitute a human-rights violation either. I believe, and will argue in the next section, that the present global institutional order is human-rights violating in that the underfulfill ment of human rights is foreseeably much greater under this order than it would be under various feasible modifications thereof. If this is true, then it follows that the existing global order is unjust by the lights of all broadly consequentialist conceptions of social justice that recognize human rights as minimal constraints on the justice of social institutions: this order is unjust by foreseeably giving rise to a greater underfulfillment of human rights than would be reasonably avoid able. Uncompensated participation in the imposition of this order can then be said to be harming those whose human rights remain unfulfilled by helping to impose upon them unjust social institutions that contribute to their predicament. In most ordinary contexts, the word "harm" is understood in an historical sense - either diachronically (someone is harmed when she is rendered worse-off than she was at some earlier time) or subjunctively (someone is harmed when she is rendered worse-off than she would have been had some earlier arrangements contin ued undisturbed). As we have seen, the second strand of my argument, operating on Lockean terrain, conceives harm in this ordinary way and then conceives justice in terms of harm: Pre vailing economic arrangements and the present economic distri bution are shown to be unjust in virtue of the fact that they harm many by forcing them below any credible state-of-nature baseline. It is worth stressing, then, that the third strand of my argument, catering to broadly consequentialist conceptions of social justice, does not, pace Satz,31 conceive justice and injustice in terms of an independently specified notion of harm. Rather, this third strand 31 Satz, "Comments on Pogge's World Poverty and Human Rights." 46 THOMAS POGGE relates the concepts of harm and justice in the opposite way, conceiving harm in terms of an independently specified conception of social justice. On my ecumenical response to broadly conse quentialist conceptions of social justice, we are harming the global poor if and insofar as we collaborate in imposing unjust social institutions upon them; and social institutions are certainly unjust if and insofar as they foreseeably give rise to large-scale avoidable underfulfillment of human rights. Moreover, pace Patten,32 this third strand of my argument is not addressed to libertarians, who indeed reject any non-historical, broadly consequentialist assessment of social institutions. Libertari ans are addressed by the first and, to some extent, by the second strand. To be sure, the third strand, like the two others, is meant to support the conclusion that the immense catastrophe of world pov erty manifests not merely the affluents' failure to fulfill their positive duties, but also, and more importantly, their massive violation of their negative duties. But the moral significance of this conclusion can be appreciated far beyond the confines of the libertarian school. Nearly everyone in the affluent countries would agree that our moral duty not to contribute to the imposition of conditions of extreme poverty on people and our moral duty to help protect people from harm in whose production we are implicated in this way are each more stringent than our moral duty to help protect people from harm in whose production we are not materially involved.33 As I try to implement the third strand of my argument, specifically for a human right to basic necessities, it involves three main tasks. I seek to show that it is, among broadly consequentialist conceptions, a minimal and widely acceptable demand of justice on all national institutional schemes that these must be designed to avoid life threatening poverty insofar as this is reasonably possible. I then seek to show that this demand of justice applies not merely to any domestic institutional arrangements, but to the global order as well. And I must then show, thirdly, that there are feasible alternatives to the existing global institutional order under which life-threatening poverty would be wholly or largely avoided. 32 Patten, "Remarks on Pogge's World Poverty and Human Rights" 33 These comparisons, once again, hold constant the cost or opportunity cost of the required conduct to the duty bearers as well as the reduction in harm it brings to the beneficiaries. REAL WORLD JUSTICE 47 Task one is easy. There simply is no broadly consequentialist conception of social justice in the field that purports to justify, within one national society, radical inequality of the kind the world at large displays today. To be sure, Patten is right to point out that some libertarians (Robert Nozick) do purport to justify such extreme inequalities. But they do this by appeal to historical conceptions of social justice; and I have sketched my response to such justifications in the preceding section. Task two involves a highly complex argument to which I cannot possibly do justice here.34 So let me here concentrate on Task three, on which my critics have focused most of their attention. 6. The Causal Role of the Global Institutional Order in the Reproduction of Severe Poverty Many critics believe that I see the global institutional order as the main cause of world poverty. And they respond that, in light of the incompetence, corruption, and oppression prevalent in so many poor countries, this claim is simply not credible or, at the very least, unsupported by empirical evidence. They are wrong on both counts. Let us begin with a quick general reflection on causes. In the simplest cases, multiple causes add up to produce an effect. Thus the smoke in a bar is the sum of the smoke released by all the smokers. In the case of world poverty, however, the relation among causes is more complex in at least two ways. One complexity is that the dif ferent causes of poverty, such as global institutional factors and national policies, influence one another's effects.35 How harmful corrupt leaders in poor countries are, for example, is strongly influ enced by whether the global order recognizes such leaders, on the basis of effective power alone, as entitled to sell us their country's resources, to borrow in its name, and to use the proceeds to buy the means of internal repression. Given this special complexity, it is not correct to identify my assertion that most severe poverty worldwide was and is avoidable through global institutional reform with the claim that the existing global institutional order is the main cause of world poverty. My 34 See Pogge, World Poverty and Human Rights, Chapter 4, and Thomas W. Pogge, "The Incoherence between Rawls's Theories of Justice," Fordham Law Review 72(5) (2004), pp. 1739-1759. 35 Discussion of the other complexity begins six paragraphs down. 48 THOMAS POGGE assertion is perfectly compatible with the claim (which I also endorse) that most severe poverty worldwide was and is avoidable through better national policies and better social institutions in the poor countries. To put it simplistically, the interaction between the two sets of causal factors is not so much additive as multiplicative. The worse each set of factors is, the more it also aggravates the marginal harmful impact of the other. But if, as development economists like to stress, most severe poverty worldwide was and is avoidable through better national policies and better social institutions in the poor countries, does this not show that our global institutional order is morally acceptable as it is? Am I not, as Patten put it,36 demanding too much from ourselves, given that the ruling elites in the poor countries could also eradicate much poverty? Now it is true that many of these elites are incompetent, corrupt, and oppressive. Failing, as badly as we are and often worse, to honor their negative duties not to harm, they are indeed responsible for most severe poverty worldwide. But this is quite compatible with the advantaged citizens in the rich countries also being responsible for most severe poverty worldwide. For it is equally true that most such poverty was and is avoidable through a better global institutional order. Given this basic symmetry, we cannot accept Patten's judgment that we should not be required to stop our contribution until they are ready to stop theirs. If this were right, then it would be permissible for two parties together to bring about as much harm as they like, each of them pointing out that it has no obligation to stop so long as the other continues. The situation is roughly analogous to that of two upstream fac tories releasing chemicals into a river. The chemicals of each factory would cause little harm by themselves. But the mixture of chemicals from both plants causes huge harm downstream. In this sort of case, we must not hold each factory owner responsible for only the small harm he would be causing if the other did not pollute. This would leave unaccounted-for most of the harm they produce together and would thus be quite implausible. In a case of this kind, provided each factory owner knows about the effluent released by the other and can foresee the harmful effects they together produce, each owner bears responsibility for his marginal contribution, that is, for as much of the harm as would be avoided if he alone were not discharging his chemicals. Each factory owner is then responsible for most of the harm they jointly produce. 36 Patten, " Remarks on Pogge's World Poverty and Human Rights" REAL WORLD JUSTICE 49 Despite this symmetry in my causal account, my critics nonethe less have a point when they accuse me of explanatory globalism37 (in analogy to the explanatory nationalism of which I am accusing the majority of development economists38). This accusation is accurate in that I focus much more on global than on national factors. I do this, because these are the factors that my readers and I are morally responsible for and because, not unrelatedly, these factors are grossly neglected by development economists of all stripes, by the media, and by the citizens of the affluent countries for whom I am writing. And I have another reason for paying more attention to the causal role of global factors in the reproduction of massive severe poverty. This further reason depends on the second special complexity I mentioned earlier, which is that the causes of world poverty also influence one another. As the global institutional order is shaped by the political leaders of the most powerful countries, who in turn are selected and shaped by their domestic institutional arrangements, so the global institutional order powerfully shapes the national regimes especially of the weaker countries as well as the composition, incen tives, and opportunities of their ruling elites. For example, corrupt rule in poor countries is made much more likely by the fact that our global order accords such rulers, on the basis of effective power alone, the international resource and borrowing privileges just described.39 These privileges provide strong incentives to potential predators (military officers, most frequently) to take power by force and compel even the most well-intentioned rulers, if they want to maintain their hold on power, to allow such potential putschists corruptly to divert state revenues. The global order thus exerts a strong influence upon the weaker and poorer countries, which makes them considerably more likely to have corrupt and oppressive national regimes. Not all of them will have such regimes, of course, but many of them will, as is well-illustrated by Nigeria and many other developing countries in which the resource sector accounts for a large fraction of GDP.40 This 37 This accusation is due to Patten: "Remarks on Pogge's World Poverty and Human Rights," though he uses the less fitting term "explanatory cosmopolitanism." 38 See Pogge, World Poverty and Human Rights, Section 5.3. 39 See Pogge, World Poverty and Human Rights, Sections 4.9, 6.3, 6.4. 40 See Ricky Lam and Leonard Wantchekon, "Dictatorships as a Political Dutch Disease" (www.library.yale.edu/socsci/egcdp795.pdf); Leonard Wantchekon, "Why Do Resource Dependent Countries Have Authoritarian Governments?" (www.yale. edu/leitner/pdf/1999-1 l.pdf, 1999). 50 THOMAS POGGE is one more reason to focus on global factors - especially on those that affect the quality of national regimes in the poorer countries. Let us now look at the evidence I have for believing that severe poverty is largely avoidable through global institutional reforms. Because the effects of sweeping reforms are harder to assess, I discuss in some detail several small reforms and their likely effects. In the WTO negotiations, the affluent countries insisted on continued and asymmetrical protections of their markets through tariffs, quotas, anti-dumping duties, export credits, and subsidies to domestic pro ducers, greatly impairing the export opportunities of even the very poorest countries. These protections cost developing countries hun dreds of billions of dollars in lost export revenues.41 Risse believes these protections will be phased out. Let us hope so. Still, these protections certainly account for a sizable fraction of the 270 million poverty deaths since 1989. 7. Moderate and Feasible Reforms of the Global Institutional Order Are there other feasible reforms of the existing global order through which severe poverty could be largely or wholly avoided? The reform I discuss in most detail involves a small change in international property rights.42 In accordance with Locke's inalienable right to a proportional share of the world's resources or some adequate equivalent, this change would set aside a small part of the value of any natural resources used for those who would otherwise be excluded from a proportional share. I show how this GRD could comfortably raise 1% of the global social product specifically for poverty eradication. And I outline how these funds could be spent so as to provide strong incentives toward better government in the developing countries. The proposed GRD in the amount of 1 % of the global product would currently raise about $320 billion annually, or 86 times what all affluent countries combined are now spending on basic social services in the developing world. What sort of impact would this money have? Consider health care. The WHO Commission on Macroeconomics and Health, chaired by Jeffrey Sachs, has put the 41 See Pogge, World Poverty and Human Rights, Section IV. 42 See Pogge, World Poverty and Human Rights, Chapter 8. REAL WORLD JUSTICE 51 cost of providing basic medical care in the developing world at $62 billion annually and has estimated that this initiative alone would prevent about 8 million deaths from poverty-related causes each year.43 Another $20 billion could go to incentivize research into the so-called neglected diseases which, because they affect mostly the poor, are grossly under-researched thus far: hepatitis, meningitis, dengue fever, leprosy, sleeping sickness, Chagas disease, river blind ness, leishmaniasis, Buruli ulcer, lymphatic filariasis, bilharzia, ma laria, tuberculosis, and pneumonia. There would be money to give every human being access to clean water and electricity. There would be money for free nutritious meals in schools that children could attend free of charge (thanks to the International Monetary Fund, many schools in developing countries are now charging attendance fees). There would be money to subsidize micro-lending which has been highly effective in recent decades even while charging interest rates of around 20%. And there would be money to relieve the crushing debt burden - often accumulated under wholly undemo cratic regimes - that is weighing down many of the poorest coun tries.44 Critics have worried about domestic cooperation. But how many governments would refuse the offer to spend large amounts of money in their country? Consider India, which has about 30% of the world's poor and currently receives about $1.7 billion annually in all kinds of official development assistance from all rich countries combined. Under the reform, some 96 billion dollars of GRD funds could be 43 The Economist (22 December 2001), pp. 82-83. 44 An especially dramatic example of this perverse consequence of the interna tional borrowing privilege is played out in Rwanda: Perhaps there was no better reflection of the world's shabby treatment of post genocide Rwanda than the matter of the debt burden incurred by the Habyari mana government. The major source of the unpaid debt was the weapons the regime had purchased for the war against the RPF, which had then been turned against innocent Tutsi during the genocide. ... incredibly enough, the new gov ernment was deemed responsible for repaying to those multilateral and national lenders the debt accrued by its predecessors. The common-sense assumption that Rwanda deserved and could not recover without special treatment and, that the debt would have been wiped out more or less automatically, had no currency in the world of international finance. Instead of Rwanda receiving vast sums of money as reparations by those who had failed to stop the tragedy, it in fact owed those same sources a vast sum of money. [International Panel of Eminent Personalities, Rwan da: The Preventable Genocide, 7 July 2000 (www.visiontv.ca/RememberRwanda/ Report.pdf), Sections 17.30 and 17.33]. 52 THOMAS POGGE spent there, greatly benefiting also India's pharmaceutical industry, its agricultural sector, its construction firms, its minimum wage level, its unemployment rate, and its tax intake. India's politicians would be extremely eager to cooperate in securing India's share of the GRD funds. The GRD, though it re-channels money from the consumers of resources to the global poor, is not, pace Satz,45 a form of aid. It does not take away some of what belongs to the affluent. Rather, it modifies conventional property rights so as to give legal effect to an inalienable moral right of the poor. For libertarians, this is the right not to be deprived of a decent start in life through a grievously unjust historical process. For Locke, this is the pre-institutional right not to be excluded, without equivalent substitute, from a proportional share of the world's resources. For broadly consequentialist theorists of justice, this is the right not to have imposed upon one an institutional order that is unjust by virtue of the fact that under this order, fore seeably and avoidably, many human beings cannot meet their most basic needs. Alan Patten claims that mine is just an exercise in re-labeling. But by assuming that I must really be calling for aid and assistance, he is begging the question I raise. Our moral failure in the face of world poverty is a mere failure to aid only if we really are morally entitled to the huge advantages we enjoy, from birth, under present institutional arrangements. And this is exactly what I am denying - by appeal to how our advantages arose historically, by appeal to Locke's resource share criterion, and by appeal to the massive life-threatening poverty to which the existing global institutional order foreseeably and avoidably exposes the majority of humankind. Patten worries that if the rich countries were to implement my proposals, they and their citizens would be unfairly disadvantaged vis-?-vis the elites of many poor countries who would continue to refuse to shoulder their fair share of the cost of eradicating global poverty.46 The details of the GRD proposal show that no country could avoid the levy on resource uses without incurring even greater surcharges on their exports (and possibly imports as well). Still, Patten is right that some politically privileged people in poor coun tries (and some economically privileged people in rich countries!) will 45 Satz, "Comments on Pogge's World Poverty and Human Rights" 46 Patten, "Remarks on Pogge's World Poverty and Human Rights" REAL WORLD JUSTICE 53 manage to contribute less than their fair share to the eradication of world poverty. What is baffling is how Patten can deem this unfair ness a sufficient reason to release us from our duty to contribute. I suspect he is once more tacitly assuming here that our relevant duty is a duty to aid and that the literature on fair sharing of the burdens of positive duties is therefore relevant. Perhaps one may indeed refuse to contribute one's fair share to a morally urgent aid project on the ground that others similarly placed successfully avoid contributing theirs. But appealing to this thought again assumes what I dispute: that the status quo involves us in violating only positive duties toward the global poor. Once it is accepted that we are vio lating our negative and intermediate duties toward the poor, Patten's postulated permission seems absurd. One may not refuse to bear the opportunity cost of ceasing to harm others on the ground that others similarly placed continue their harming. Thus, in particular, we are not entitled to go on inflicting harm upon the global poor on the ground that others (preditorial elites in the poor countries) are also continuing. Likewise, we may stop some from harming third parties, and compel some to mitigate harms they have caused, even when we are unable so to stop and to compel all who do harm in a similar way. Thus, in particular, we are no more barred from setting up a GRD by the fact that some of the affluent would unfairly escape its effects than we are barred from setting up a criminal-justice system by the fact that some crimes and criminals are unfairly neither prevented, nor deterred, nor punished. Yes, some will get away with murder or with enriching themselves by starving the poor. But this sad fact neither permits us to join their ranks, nor forbids us to reduce such crimes as far as we can. Centre for Applied Philosophy and Public Ethics Australian National University Canberra ACT 0200 Australia E-mail: tp6@columbia.edu Article Contents p. [29] p. 30 p. 31 p. 32 p. 33 p. 34 p. 35 p. 36 p. 37 p. 38 p. 39 p. 40 p. 41 p. 42 p. 43 p. 44 p. 45 p. 46 p. 47 p. 48 p. 49 p. 50 p. 51 p. 52 p. 53 Issue Table of Contents The Journal of Ethics, Vol. 9, No. 1/2, Current Debates in Global Justice (2005), pp. 1-306 Volume Information Introduction [pp. 1-9] Cosmopolitanism and Global Justice [pp. 11-27] Real World Justice [pp. 29-53] Against Global Egalitarianism [pp. 55-79] What We Owe to the Global Poor [pp. 81-117] The Role of Apparent Constraints in Normative Reasoning: A Methodological Statement and Application to Global Justice [pp. 119-125] Do Patriotic Ties Limit Global Justice Duties? [pp. 127-150] Duties to the Distant: Aid, Assistance, and Intervention in the Developing World [pp. 151-170] The Cosmopolitan Imperative: Global Justice through Accountable Integration [pp. 171-199] Three Models of Global Community [pp. 201-224] Toward an International Rule of Law: Distinguishing International Law-Breakers from Would-Be Law-Makers [pp. 225-246] Preventive Wars, Just War Principles, and the United Nations [pp. 247-268] Does the Gats Undermine Democratic Control over Health? [pp. 269-281] Global Justice for Humans or for All Living Beings and What Difference It Makes [pp. 283-300] Back Matter work_l5ceby63sja3tlxdkhqcw35t44 ---- 42439_2019_13_Article 1..21 ORIGINAL ARTICLE Corrective Justice Among States Pavlos Eleftheriadis1 # The Author(s) 2020 Abstract The debate concerning solidarity and justice among states has missed the key contribution made to international affairs by corrective justice. Unlike distributive justice, which applies within states, corrective justice applies among states. It applies in particular to cooperative arrangements creating interdependence among them. Corrective justice does not require fairness in outcomes. It requires redress in cases of loss caused by unfairness. An illustration of corrective justice among states is the Eurozone’s response to the financial crisis. The assistance offered to the most burdened states was not as an attempt to arrive at fair shares but an attempt to remedy the losses unfairly caused by the mistakes made by the Eurozone as a whole, when designing its basic architecture. Keywords Corrective justice . Solidarity. Legitimacy. Eurozone . Fairness The question of justice among states became a pressing issue in Europe when the financial crisis of 2008 affected states in radically differently ways. The Eurozone members took steps to assist the worst affected among them: Greece, Ireland, Portugal, Spain and Cyprus.1 They made available funds for emergency loans even though the original assumption was that there would be no state bailouts.2 In due course, the members of the Eurozone sought to amend and supplement the treaties. They created a new international institution, the European Stability Mechanism by way of a treaty of international law that is not part of the EU treaties, with a mandate to assist member states in financial troubles.3 At the same time, and in a significant shift of policy, the European Central Bank started purchasing sovereign bonds. In the end, the https://doi.org/10.1007/s42439-019-00013-x 1In addition, there were also programmes of assistance to some non-Eurozone states, such as Hungary, Latvia and Romania. 2Some scholars argued against this initial assumption with regard to Art. 122(2) TFEU. See, for example, Tuori and Tuori 2014, 138 ff. 3Extensive and very helpful accounts of the constitutional legal aspects of the crisis are offered by Tuori and Tuori 2014, A. Hinarejos 2015 and F. Fabbrini 2016. * Pavlos Eleftheriadis pavlos.eleftheriadis@law.ox.ac.uk 1 Mansfield College, Oxford OX1 3TF, UK Jus Cogens (2020) 2:7–27 Published online: January202023 http://crossmark.crossref.org/dialog/?doi=10.1007/s42439-019-00013-x&domain=pdf http://orcid.org/0000-0003-1120-4650 mailto:pavlos.eleftheriadis@law.ox.ac.uk financial assistance programmes helped the burdened states weather the storm so that they all remained in the Eurozone without defaulting on their loans. All of them, however, suffered great economic damage, loss of output and high rates of unemployment. 1 From Fairness to Solidarity The Court of Justice has found that these assistance operations were lawful.4 But what was their moral character? The question remains controversial. Were they manifestations of justice, discharging an obligation of solidarity towards the weaker states? Or were they simply instances of prudence, not strictly required by law or morality, only expedient responses to an emergency? Or were these new loan far too generous, unjustly transferring resources from the responsible to the irresponsible? These are still deeply controversial questions. Some believe that the Eurozone did too little to assist its weakest members.5 Others think it did too much.6 All of these positions may rely on some conception of what is fair or unfair. These matters depend on our interpretation of the purpose and nature of the Eurozone agreements, but they also turn on deeper assumptions about the moral obligations arising out of long-term cooperation. The vocabulary of justification is not optional in this context. Fairness is always a matter closely connected to any interpretation of agreements between two or more parties. This is so both as a matter of the moral character of law in general, as many legal philosophers have shown,7 but also as a matter of the specific moral requirements of agreements, including international agreements. In many jurisdictions, for example, the law requires ‘good faith’ in the interpretation and enforcement of contracts, espe- cially in cases where cooperation is for an indefinite period. The distinguished English judge Tom Bingham described the role that fairness in the interpretation of long-term agreements in English and foreign law as follows: In many civil law systems, and perhaps in most legal systems outside the common law world, the law of obligations recognises and enforces an overriding principle that in making and carrying out contracts parties should act in good faith. This does not simply mean that they should not deceive each other, a principle which any legal system must recognise; its effect is perhaps most aptly conveyed by such metaphorical colloquialisms as ‘playing fair’, ‘coming clean’ or ‘putting one’s cards face upwards on the table.’ It is in essence a principle of fair open dealing … English law has, characteristically, committed itself to no such overriding 4 See Case C-370/12, Pringle, ECLI:EU:C:2012:756 and Case C-62/14, Gauweiler et al. v Deutscher Bundestag, ECLI:EU:C:2015:400, which was a preliminary reference from the German Constitutional Court in BVerfG, Beschluss des Zweiten Senats vom 14. January 2014–2 BvR 2728/13 - Rn. (1–24). 5 See, for example, A. Mody 2018 and J. E. Stiglitz 2016, 85–144. 6 For example, U. di Fabio 2014, 107–110 and H. W. Sinn 2014, 343. Sinn thought that rather than new loans, Greece should have been given significant debt relief: “The right mixture of debt relief, privatization, and wealth levies could be jointly negotiated in a Paris Club debt conference convened to reset the Eurozone. The European debt crisis has many causes, and creditors and debtors alike share the responsibility. A way to distribute the burden fairly should thus be sought—and it is important that it be found soon”, 343. 7 For this general view of law, see R. Dworkin 1986, N. E. Simmonds 2007, R. Alexy 2009. Jus Cogens (2020) 2:7–278 principle but has developed piecemeal solutions in response to demonstrated problems of unfairness.8 In the USA, the Second Restatement of Contracts requires that “[e]very contract imposes upon each party a duty of good faith and fair dealing in its performance and enforcement”.9 English law takes a narrower view, but it too does not always enforce contracts that parties willingly entered into, if their terms are ‘unconscionable’ or are the result of undue influence exercised due to unequal bargaining power.10 So even in England, unfairness can occasionally be a reason for holding a deal unenforceable. Whatever the position in contract law, the principle of ‘good faith’ is also an established principle of the interpretation of treaties of international law. Article 26 of the Vienna Convention of the law of Treaties, which bears the title ‘pacta sunt servanda’ simply states: ‘Every treaty in force is binding upon the parties to it and must be performed by them in good faith’11. The reference to ‘good faith’ means that any interpretation is subject to its context and may evolve with the expectations of the parties.12 The general rules are that a treaty is to be interpreted in good faith in accordance with the ordinary meaning to be given to the terms of the treaty ‘in their context’ and in ‘the light of its object and purpose’ because ‘each of these elements guide the interpreter in establishing what the Parties actually intended, or their common will’.13 It follows, therefore, that the justification of the assistance programmes as a matter of the law of treaties of the Eurozone can turn on issues of ‘good faith’ or fairness. It cannot simply be a matter of the narrow reading of explicit technical rules. Whether the law permits such assistance will depend on the context, intention and nature of the parties that entered into the Eurozone agreements as these evolved over time. These general accounts of fairness do not decide the issue of the fairness of the Eurozone. They do, however, put the question of solidarity in context as a specific manifestation of a well-known question. Long-term agreements, be they private or agreements among states, must be interpreted in light of a theory of fairness, but they do not always create obligations of solidarity. Whether fairness requires solidarity will depend on the specific terms and practices of each specific agreement. If the Eurozone agreements do create such obligations, it must be for a reason. Most theorists say that no such reason exists, given how the Eurozone agreements are currently structured. 8 Interfoto Picture Library Ltd v Stilletto Visual Programmes Ltd [1989] 1 Q.B. 433, 439. See also Director General of Fair Trading v First National Bank [2001] UKHL 52, [2002] 1 A.C. 507 at [17] (Lord Bingham of Cornhill). 9 Restatement (Second) of Contracts para.205. cf. Uniform Commercial Code s.1–203. See R. S. Summers 2000, 118–144. 10 A relevant case is Lloyds Bank Ltd v Bundy [1974] EWCA 8, [1975] QB 326, where Lord Denning summarized the doctrine of ‘inequality of bargaining power’ as follows: ‘By virtue of it, the English law gives relief to one who, without independent advice, enters into a contract or transfers property for a consideration which is grossly inadequate, when his bargaining power is grievously impaired by reason of his own needs or desires, or by his own ignorance or infirmity, coupled with undue influences or pressures brought to bear on him by or for the benefit of the other’. The House of Lords has refused to endorse such a wide principle, however. 11 For an interpretation see Dorr and Schmalenbach 2011), 427–451. 12 For this point, see E. Bjorge 2015, 189, especially at 203–204. 13 The quotes are from the ‘Decision regarding delimitation of the border between Eritrea and Ethiopia’, XXV Reports of International Arbitral Awards (2002), 83–195, at 109–110. “The meaning of these Treaties is thus a central feature of this dispute. In interpreting them, the Commission will apply the general rule that a treaty is to be interpreted in good faith in accordance with the ordinary meaning to be given to the terms of the treaty in their context and in the light of its object and purpose. Each of these elements guides the interpreter in establishing what the Parties actually intended, or their ‘common will’, as Lord McNair put it in the Palena award”. Jus Cogens (2020) 2:7–27 9 http://www.bailii.org/ew/cases/EWCA/1974/8.html The German philosopher Jürgen Habermas writes that the present economic rationales of the Eurozone are incompatible with social justice and democratic legitimacy: ‘A technocracy without democratic roots would not have the motivation to accord sufficient weight to the demands of the electorate for a just distribution of income and property, for status security, public services and collective goods when these conflict with the systemic demands for competitiveness and economic growth’14 Habermas contrasts ‘technocratic’ blueprints for dealing with the crisis and a project for a ‘supranational democracy in the core of Europe’.15 By the term ‘democratic roots’, Habermas seems to imply that solidarity needs to be supported by the identification of each person with a single political community as its citizen. He says that the EU’s ‘technocratic’ response runs the risk of lacking ‘the motivation to accord sufficient weight to the demands of the electorate for a just distribution of income and property, for status security, public services and collective goods when these conflict with the systemic demands for competitiveness and economic growth’.16 Habermas’ argument has a compelling logic, which is shared by standard defences of the welfare state. The argument assumes that citizens of the same state will have the psychological motivation to recognize a duty of solidarity to one another, normally expressed by ideas and principles of social justice. Indeed, the EU treaties recognize the division of the Union into states and an associated division of them into welfare states.17 As a matter of fact, European citizens do not feel the same identification with those they consider outsiders. Europe’s task, therefore, is to expand outward the bonds of community that exist within states. This is why Habermas argues that the Union needs to create its own ‘democratic roots’ in common identification. If this argument is right, then the introduction of meaningful solidarity in the European Union presupposes the profound transformation of its institutions. Habermas is clearly aware of the seriousness of the political challenge. He proposes a ‘real political union’, which will change the circumstances of European citizens.18 Social justice can then become a component of a sharing in power under the institutions of a political community. In order to achieve solidarity, we will need to abandon borders within Europe to produce a single, integrated political community. Is this a valid argument? I do not think it is. I do not doubt the positive aspect of the argument. Of course, a political community creates bonds of solidarity. I do wish to challenge, however, the negative part, namely, the claim that solidarity does not apply when persons are not bound by the deep bonds of citizenship. In my view, obligations of solidarity can arise from relations among persons or, indeed, from relations among states and other collective bodies, when they engage with one another in the right way. Solidarity does not always require a relationship of citizenship. Other relations can have the same result. The key to the argument is that obligations of solidarity arise as acts of assistance under a principle of mutual aid or as a principle of redress. These are not matters of justice in distribution but matters of corrective justice. This point has been obscured by most discussions of solidarity in the European Union, where the dominant language is that of distributive claims. 14 J. Habermas 2015a, 101 and J. Habermas 2015b. For a parallel argument see R. Forst 2015, 227–234. 15 J. Habermas 2015a, 98. 16 J. Habermas 2015a, 95–107, at 101. See also J. Habermas 2013. 17 This point is also well set out in J. Neyer 2012, 35–55. For an interesting debate on this between Neyer (who sees the European Union as a project that does not seek to be federal) and Forst (who follows Habermas in accepting the federalist interpretation), see J. Neyer 2015, 211–226 and R. Forst 2015, 227–234. 18 J. Habermas 2015a, 100. Jus Cogens (2020) 2:7–2710 2 Distributive Claims The European Union treaties are not silent on solidarity. Article 3(3) TEU provides that the Union shall ‘promote social justice’ and promote ‘economic, social and territorial cohesion, and solidarity among Member States’. Solidarity is also mentioned in Article 122 TFEU in the context of assistance in emergencies, whereby the Council may decide ‘in a spirit of solidarity between member states’ on measures assisting a state if ‘severe difficulties arise in the supply of certain products, notably in the area of energy’. This article, however, was not invoked in the case of the financial assistance programmes. It is not entirely clear, however, what these general statements mean. Perhaps, like other general statements in this part of the treaties, they do not intend to create clear obligations, moral or legal, on the institutions of the European Union or the member states.19 They are supplemented, however, by the mention of solidarity in particular policies. Solidarity is mentioned in the context of asylum policies20 the general ‘solidarity clause’ in case of natural or man-made disasters,21 and in the detailed mechanism for distributions of funds to the member states. These funds are very important for the distribution of resources from the wealthier states to the poorer ones. They were created at various points in the history of the Union and are now provided for in the treaties. The European Social Fund is covered by articles 162 to 164 TFEU, Structural Funds are provided for in article 175 TFEU, and a Regional Development Fund is provided by article 176 TFEU. The treaty empowers the EU to distribute funds with the aim of improving employment opportunities; strengthening social inclusion; fighting poverty; promoting education, skills and life-long learning; and developing active, comprehensive and sustainable inclusion policies.22 Nevertheless, the total amount of spending on such projects is very small, at least in relation to the overall EU economy. It is also very small in proportion to similar funds available within each state for social purposes. In the member states, the equivalent spending ranges between 35% and 58% of gross domestic product. In the total EU budget, the equivalent amount is only about 1% of the gross national income of the 28 member states.23 According to an estimate made by the Institute of Fiscal Studies, the EU’s total spending on structural, cohesion and agriculture and rural development funds accounted for about 38% of the total EU spending in 2014. The scale of redistribution involved is therefore very modest indeed. The direct European Union social spending is about 20 or 30 times less than what occurs within a member state. The small size of these transfers strengthens the argument that solidarity in the European Union is not really a functional principle. Solidarity may be an exclusive preserve of the member states operating only within their separate political communities. 19 See E. Küçük 2016, 965–983 and M. Ross 2010, 23–45. For a discussion of the (relatively limited) role of the Charter of Fundamental Rights in the protection of social welfare rights, see S. O’Leary 2005, 39–87. 20 See Article 67 TFEU and Article 80 TFEU. The principle has not, however, made any difference in practice. See Joined Cases C-411/10 and C-493/10 N.S. and M.E., EU:C:2011:865, par. 93. 21 Article 222 TFEU. 22 The rules of distribution of these sums are set out in Regulation (EU) No 1304/2013 of the European Parliament and of the Council of December 17, 2013 on the European Social Fund and repealing Council Regulation (EC) No 1081/2006, OJ L 347, 20.12.2013, 470–486. The Regulation provides for common principles for the implementation of five European Structural and Investment Funds: the European Regional Development Fund (ERDF), the European Social Fund (ESF), the Cohesion Fund, the European Agricultural Fund for Rural Development (EAFRD) and the European Maritime and Fisheries Fund (EMFF). The treaty articles are also supplemented by Protocol No 28 on economic, social and territorial cohesion. 23 See Browne et al. 2016. Jus Cogens (2020) 2:7–27 11 Many sophisticated commentators observe that the social dimension of the EU is minimal. Commenting on the ‘patchwork’ of social justice provisions in EU law, Gráinne de Búrca writes that solidarity had a ‘constructive potential’ which could gradually ‘promote a degree of solidarity and mutual responsibility—however tentative and limited at first—between states, citizens, and other residents within the enlarging European space’.24 Such cautious endorse- ments of solidarity, however, cannot hide the fact that social justice is a very small part of the EU. Any authors thus take the view that, since the EU is not a state, the normal rules of distributive justice do not apply to it. Since solidarity or social justice is a principle that only applies within states (or equivalent political communities), no solidarity principle applies in the European Union, at least not yet.25 In this vein, Professor Christian Joerges, a leading scholar on European Union law, argues that the European Union is incapable of having a proper policy towards social justice. Joerges refers to an argument made by Friedrich Carl von Savigny, the leading German legal scholar of the nineteenth century, that justice applies to private relations but not to the relations between states. In Joerges’ reading, Savigny has shown that ‘interstate relations … remain in an unruly state of nature governed by power and politics rather than law’.26 From Savigny’s premise, Joerges draws the conclusion that the European Monetary Union is incapable of imposing a uniform architecture of social policy. It does not have the means. Europe has instead created a competitive ‘single market’ where each state seeks to have a social policy on its own, allowing for great ‘socioeconomic diversity’, which the institutions of the EU cannot address. Joerges adds that the various economies have diverged rather than converged since the creation of the Union. Europe’s idea of ‘a highly competitive social market economy’ results in the undermining of social justice and solidarity everywhere in the EU. He says that ‘the socioeconomic diversity of the Union was treated with benign neglect and an institutional framework with the potential to manage the implication of this move was not established’.27 He finds this ‘fateful’ for the ‘prospects of Social Europe’.28 The only policy that, for Joerges, is working at EU level is that emanating from the European Central Bank, which in his view is insensitive to the concerns of social justice. Hence, the ‘Maastricht arrangement was an ill- defined political compromise, rather than a sustainable accomplishment of constitutional validity and strength’, which has led to ‘authoritarian managerialism’.29 The only way of overcoming this stalemate, for Joerges, is through the creation of a ‘transnational democracy’ through federal institutions. He insists that such a transformation is urgent, because the present arrangements do not provide a solid basis for solidarity and social justice.30 A similar view has been taken by Floris de Witte, who has offered an extensive and original discussion of the question of social justice in the EU. De Witte argues that ‘justice is an associative commitment: it is born and sustained by the interaction between particular groups of citizens’.31 Nevertheless, de Witte’s discussion locates justice firmly within the framework and architecture of institutions of the state. De Witte argues that the existence of the European 24 G. de Búrca 2005, 9. 25 This is a view reflected in the writings of influential legal scholars. It is the view, for example, defended by A. Williams 2010), A. Somek 2015, 295–310, and N. Walker 2015, 247–258. 26 C. Joerges 2017, 92–119, at 94 (citing from Savigny’s System des Heutigen Römischen Rects, vol. III, 1849). 27 C. Joerges 2017, 107. 28 C. Joerges 2017, 107. 29 C. Joerges 2017, 111. Joerges follows here similar arguments made by F. W. Scharpf 2002, 645–70. 30 A similar view is taken by Frank Vandenbroucke, who proposes a new ‘Social Union’ as the appropriate response to the current absence of proper institutions of solidarity. See F. Vandenbroucke 2017, 3–46. 31 de Witte 2008, 208. Jus Cogens (2020) 2:7–2712 Union ‘ensures that the associative connections between citizens across borders are incorpo- rated within the pursuit of justice on the national level’.32 In effect, the EU brings citizens closer to one another, by putting them ‘in a social relationship’ in the sense that ‘all EU citizens are part of the incipient and ill-defined European polity’ but also on ‘the national level, where citizens of different nationalities engage with each other through a whole range of social interactions’.33 But de Witte concludes that since the EU is in effect an international project, it does not have the potential for justice: ‘The EU does not dispose of the institutional sophistication required in order legitimately to articulate an autonomous conception of supra- national justice…. In consequence, the EU cannot engage in the definition of supranational ideas of equality, fairness, or distributive justice in a legitimate way’.34 Surprisingly perhaps, Joerges and De Witte are in agreement with the former Finance Minister of Germany, Wolfgang Schäuble. In a widely leaked ‘non-paper’ to the ministers of the Eurogroup on the occasion of his departure from his post in November 2017, Dr. Schäuble gave a detailed account of his overall assessment of the Eurozone, where he also expresses scepticism about the potential of the European Union to achieve social justice. It lacks both of the mechanism for redistribution and the required institutions of democratic accountability. The paper states that the Ministry’s view fiscal responsibilities and fiscal control belong together. The paper observes that there are only two ways in which the EU could maintain the symmetry of responsibilities and control: Either we transfer parts of national sovereignty and control of fiscal rules to the EU level (“Euro Finance Minister”), together with a greater democratic legitimacy. This would certainly require EU treaty changes to be credible. Or we agree on an intergovernmental solution.35 The real choice here appears to be between full union and loose integovernmentalism. The ‘non-paper’ by the Finance Ministry, just like Joerges, De Witte and Habermas, relies on the assumption that an intergovernmental institutional setting is an inappropriate institutional arrangement for the operation of solidarity. The paper therefore proposes further political union through treaty change as a priority for the future. But, as long as ‘there is little willingness for treaty changes, we should follow a pragmatic two-step approach: Intergovern- mental solution now, to be transposed into EU law later on’.36 In summary, the views I have examined by Habermas, Joerges and De Witte make the following negative claim: they suggest that solidarity is strictly limited to the national domain and cannot develop in an international context. I will now argue that this assumption is mistaken. I reject the premise that solidarity applies only within states and that solidarity does not apply to international or intergovernmental structures. In order to understand this point, we need to expand our scope beyond familiar assumptions about the domestic welfare state. I will argue that solidarity is not identical to distribution. Solidarity has in fact two distinct grounds, 32 Ibid. 33 de Witte 2008, 123. 34 de Witte 2008, 210. 35 Available at: https://www.scribd.com/document/361120275/German-finance-ministry-non-paper-on- Eurozone-reforms. 36 These views seem to correspond to standard views among German economists. It is common place in German economics departments that within the Eurozone ‘ever member country has to do its homework and that relying on bailouts from others distorts incentives’. See Brunnermeier et al. 2016, 97. Jus Cogens (2020) 2:7–27 13 https://www.scribd.com/document/361120275/German-finance-ministry-non-paper-on-Eurozone-reforms https://www.scribd.com/document/361120275/German-finance-ministry-non-paper-on-Eurozone-reforms one in distributive justice and one in corrective justice. Only distributive justice is restricted to the domestic case. 3 Distributive and Corrective Justice Although the distinction between distributive and corrective justice is old and well understood, it has not, for the most part, been deployed in the debates concerning international justice.37 It appears that when scholars refer to justice in the international context, they only have in mind distributive claims. If distributive claims cannot be justified, then justice is irrelevant.38 These views seem to work on the presupposition, or at least the mental picture, of justice relying on a central distribution of a good to beneficiaries according to criteria of need or merit. This is the typical model of the distribution of fair shares outlined by Aristotle and repeated many times in modern philosophy. It is the standard model of distributive justice as justice in distribution. John Rawls too identifies social justice with distributive justice when he says on the ‘subject of justice’ that: ‘the primary subject of [social] justice is the basic structure of society, or more exactly, the way in which the major social institutions distribute fundamental rights and duties and determine the division of advantages from social cooperation’ (emphasis added).39 In the case of the state, the distribution takes place through central taxation and social welfare schemes. The distribution is not from state resources, but effectively from the mostly better off taxpayers to the least well off, as they receive public assistance through public funds or through freely available services, such as education and health care. It is clear that such a model of justice cannot apply to the European Union. First, there is no central taxing authority collecting public funds. Second, there is no central spending power of such funds. Third, there are not in place any institutions with the appropriate democratic powers for deciding on the appropriate test of distribution, since the European Parliament cannot have such powers. Fourth, we do not have clear institutions for the accountability of such decisions. Fifth, we do not have the underlying ‘community’ or ‘demos’ which would see the public support the transfer of funds from one part of the community to another and give meaning to mechanisms of participation as we – more or less – have in the conventional welfare systems of the states. For these reasons, the advocates of political union as a pre- condition of institutions of solidarity, such as Habermas, di Fabio and Joerges, must be right to rule out a general distributive principle for the European Union under the present institutional arrangements. If social justice makes sense only within a territorial state, then it can have no application to the European Union as it is today. This argument, however, is not the end of the matter as far as solidarity is concerned. It fails to take into account the way in which solidarity works in other ways. The relations between states just like the relations of persons are subject to a second dimension of justice, which since Aristotle we call ‘corrective justice’. Corrective justice does not provide for the distribution of something from a central source or state but accounts for the just relations among two or more 37 See for a valuable exception, T. Campos 2017, where the right to health is recast as an obligation of corrective or ‘commutative’ justice and not ‘distributive’ justice. 38 This assumption is implicit, I think, in T. Nagel 2005, 113, where ‘social justice’ is identified with justice in distribution. 39 J. Rawls 1999a, 6. Rawls refers to Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics 1129b-1130b in support of his view of social justice; J. Rawls 1999a, 9. Jus Cogens (2020) 2:7–2714 parties in the event of cooperation, exchange or reparation.40 Corrective justice addresses injustice by restoring the original positions between a person that suffered a loss and the person who gained a profit from the other’s expense. The just redress is the arithmetic mean between the part of the earner and the part of the loser.41 In Ernest Weinrib’s apt description, the organizing idea is that of correlativity. The ‘elements of liability under corrective justice can be explicated only in terms of concepts whose normative force applies simultaneously to both parties’.42 Unlike distributive justice, corrective justice takes the parties to be equal. For corrective justice ‘liability involves a conception of fairness that recognizes the equal normative status of the two parties and treats their normative positions as mirror images of each other’.43 These ideas have generated some very sophisticated arguments about the substance of the law of tort, contract and unjust enrichment. There is no need to rely on these theories in any detail here. What we need for the purposes of our argument is only the idea that states are independent agents, similar to corporations or other collective agents that are subject to private law when they are cooperating towards a common project, sharing in the process rights, obligations and risks. Such relations create mutual moral obligations from each state to all others that are analogous to legal obligations arising in contract law. I say that are merely analogous and not identical, because there is no contract law in the international sphere. Strictly speaking, since there is no central power of enforcement in international law, and since all legal obligations are to some extent provisional under public international law, there cannot be contract law in the strict sense. Under international law, states can have obligations of law to one another, but they cannot rely on the jurisdiction of a common court to enforce them. So the analogy with contract is incomplete. Still however, states do owe each other duties on the basis of their agreements. That states have mutual obligations to one another which is not an original thought. In the Law of Peoples, Rawls argues that the international community must be based on principles of fairness that apply to states. He argues that such principles would have been adopted by well- ordered peoples in a hypothetical original position for the ‘law of peoples’. In Rawls’ account, the relevant agents are the peoples and not their citizens. He argues that inequalities between states will be unjust ‘because of their unjust effects on the basic structure of the Society of Peoples, and on relations among peoples and among their members’.44 He further argues that in such a scenario, the parties will ‘formulate guidelines for setting up cooperative organiza- tions, and will agree to standards of fairness for trade as well as to certain provisions for mutual assistance’.45 Nevertheless, the relevant principle of justice does not presuppose a central distributing power. It applies in a decentralized way among the various states, as a self- imposed constraint on their foreign policies by way of ‘cooperative organizations’ and other agreements. In this account, the principles of international justice bind states in their mutual relations: they create obligations to exercise a particular kind of policy or to discharge their natural duties to each other. A principle of mutual aid is part of these obligations. One of the eight principles of the law of peoples is that ‘peoples have a duty to assist other peoples living under 40 For a general historical account of Aristotle’s distinction between distributive and corrective justice see, I. Englard 2009. 41 See I. Englard 2009, 8. 42 E. J. Weinrib 2012, 10. 43 Ibid. 44 J. Rawls 1999a, 113. 45 J. Rawls 1999a, 115. Jus Cogens (2020) 2:7–27 15 unfavourable conditions that prevent their having a just or decent political and social re- gime’.46 The obligation to assist binds peoples but exists only up the point at which societies overcome ‘unfavourable conditions’. This is not strictly speaking a matter of the distribution of resources between the parties, but the one off lifting of our fellow human beings from a state of destitution. Rawls’ principle of aid is solidarity in assistance, not solidarity in achieving fair shares.47 Although Rawls does not use the term ‘corrective justice’ for this type of bilateral obligation, it is clear that what he has in mind for the Law of Peoples is very different from the kind of justice that applies to the basic structure of a single political community. It is not a principle of distribution of fair shares but a bilateral relationship crated by the face-to-face encounter of one person or one state with another. The claim arises because of desperate need of the burdened person or state, not because of a pattern of distribution. This is a different moral relationship to that of citizenship. When we encounter each other as citizens, we look at the whole picture in relation to a vertically organized system of authority to which we both contribute. We then raise the question of the existence of inequality in the distribution of ‘primary goods’ among us buy that vertical system of authority. In the international domain, by contrast, our encounters are structured in a purely horizontal way by way of ‘cooperative’ agreements, without a vertically organized system of authority guiding our actions or resolving our disputes. The relevant domain of justice here is created by horizontal relations only. Rawls presents the obligations of solidarity or justice in the international case as arising out of the reasonable terms under which states would join a system of international law as equals. Rawls’ argument introduces in this way the idea that fairness should be a precondition of general international law, whatever else agreements may establish as binding obligations. In this view, the horizontal principle of fairness is a background condition for the continuing legitimacy of the international community as a whole, including the multilateral treaties among its members. The best way in which we can understand such a non-distributive principle of fairness is as a principle of corrective justice, similar to that giving rise to a duty of mutual aid. It arises – just as it does with persons – from the very fact of the vulnerability of states towards natural disasters or other misfortunes.48 If a prosperous state is in a position to provide aid to a burdened state without risk to itself, it has a duty to do so. A similar principle of corrective justice covers the cooperative practices of international law in the following way. If states engage with one another – as they should – in setting up complex cooperative arrangements in the course of international relations, then they are bound by the terms of fairness towards one another, just like motorists sharing a road are bound by the rules of negligence for accidents. We often call this aspect of justice ‘cooperative justice’. The distinction between distributive and corrective justice has one important consequence for the European Union. It suggests that the simple disjunction drawn by the Habermas and 46 J. Rawls 1999a, 37. 47 There is an analogy with the idea of a duty of mutual aid among strangers. Such a duty is ethically fundamental outside any legal or institutional framework. I follow here B. Herman 1984, 577–602, who applies the idea of the ‘dependence’ of human beings to the process of the categorical imperative and concludes: ‘The duty of mutual aid has its ground in the facts that we are dependent beings with ends it is not rational for us to forgo: ends set by “true needs” whose satisfaction is a necessary condition for the exercise of rationality. As we are rational agents, we set ends… As a person’s true needs are those which must be met if he is to function (or continue to function) as a rational, end-setting agent, respecting the humanity of others involves acknowledging the duty of mutual aid: one must be prepared to support the conditions of the rationality of others (their capacity to set and act for ends) when they are unable to do so without help’ (p. 597). See also B. Herman 2012, 391–411. 48 By analogy with dependent human beings, as in B. Herman 1984. Jus Cogens (2020) 2:7–2716 Joerges between independence and solidarity was not correct. Remember that they assumed that there were only two ways forward as far as the future of the Eurozone was concerned: either a decentralized and international fiscal order in which each country was exclusively liable for its own debt or a fully integrated fiscal union in which spending powers are transferred to a European authority. The distinction necessarily assumed that there could not be a sharing of burdens or a practice of solidarity in an international union, without some form of integrated political union. This is correct, only as far as distributive justice is concerned. If there is no single political power to tax the parties and distribute the shares justly, then it makes no sense of speaking of ‘just shares’. The question is very different if we are asking about something else. Solidarity in the form of mutual aid does make sense without a central authority doing the sharing. Corrective justice that arises from international cooperation does not require political union. The question that corrective justice asks is not one of fair shares, but of fair redress for a wrong. If parties provide redress to one another for the wrongs they committed, they exhibit solidarity outside a distributive framework. If I drive carelessly and I cause a cyclist to lose their balance, I owe them a duty of reparation, even if it is only an apology. If I have injured them I must provide appropriate redress. If I ignore my moral obligation to another person in need of aid, I show – among other things – a lack of solidarity. It is the same with states. A state may owe to another state some form of redress, for example, the return of a cultural artefact stolen by some of the first state’s citizens (e.g. the Parthenon marbles looted by Lord Elgin) or compensation for an oil spill caused by a military vessel. This sense of solidarity is entirely familiar from private law. There is no reason for not following the same principle in international relations. The best example of this kind of obligation in international relations is the granting of debt forgiveness as an obligation under the doctrine of ‘odious debt’ in international law.49 Under certain – very demanding – conditions, the debts assumed by a corrupt government may not be held to bind a subsequent democratic government. The doctrine of ‘odious debt’ holds that the debt must be unlawful and therefore invalid. A lender should not seek to exploit a dictator’s greed for one’s personal profit. Contract law has a similar doctrine about contracts whose object is unlawful. Under that doctrine, Cuba and the USA refused to recognize Cuba’s debts that had been taken by the Spanish colonial government just before Cuba’s independence.50 The same applied to loans taken by the Costa Rican government in the dying days of the dictator Federico Tinoco’s corrupt regime.51 In all these cases, fairness in substance was deemed more important than the terms of an existing agreement, which was considered invalid. Of course, the theory of ‘odious debt’ cannot conceivably apply to any member of the European Union. The issues are entirely different. All the members of the Eurozone are democracies and have democratically approved the original accession to the European Monetary Union as well as any amendments to the treaties. They have borrowed in the international markets exercising their constitutional powers in fiscal policy. Nevertheless, the rule of odious debt may help us understand the basic principle, namely, that fairness 49 R. Howse 2007, J. King 2016. 50 See R. Howse 2007, 10–11. 51 Aguilar-Amory and Royal Bank of Canada claims (Great Britain v Costa Rica) (1923) 1RIAA 371. See R. Howse 2007, 11–12. Jus Cogens (2020) 2:7–27 17 applies more generally as a background principle for all international institutional arrangements. 52 The general point is this. Ιf cooperative fairness creates international obligations under a principle of corrective justice in some cases of international interaction, then it can also create obligations in a process of market integration such as that provided for by the European Union treaties. In the most direct case, if a state suffers a loss because of the wrongful action of another state, it is then entitled to redress, and failure to provide it is a failure to exhibit appropriate solidarity. Indeed, the European Union has created exactly such mechanisms. It provides redress for violations of the law through the Commission and the Court of Justice. But we are entitled to ask if corrective justice creates further moral obligations of fairness or solidarity among states on the basis of their cooperation. We need to refine the argument by asking in particular who can be responsible for the joint decisions of a cooperative agreement such as the European Union. 4 Structural Responsibility The principle of mutual aid applies between two parties that encounter each other in a certain way. The case of international cooperation in trade agreements is more complex. The parties organize their relationship based on common rules and monitored by multi-lateral institutions. Here, the argument for a principle of cooperative fairness must take a modified form. By entering the founding treaties, the member states jointly created institutions of cooperation, such as the Commission, the Council, the European Parliament and – more recently – the European Central Bank. Such institutions make decisions in the name of the organization as a whole. Some of these decisions are highly consequential. They may determine a member states’ social and economic future. These common institutions are not entirely independent nor do they enjoy comprehensive powers. The member states retain economic decision-making and exercise some element of control through the Council of ministers (and through their delegates at the European Parliament). The member states remain, therefore, key decision- makers and are to that extent responsible for what the EU does.53 At the same time, we cannot hold the states responsible for everything that the EU does. But since the member states created the basic structure, such as the single market and the free movement of persons, goods, services and capital and if we can detect some economic outcomes – positive or negative – with these structures, then the member states can be held to be jointly responsible for them. This is not an entirely original thought. Something similar may already exist in the structures of global economy. It is common ground that the current structures of economic globalization are the conscious result of policy decisions made by the leading economic powers, for example, the global financial architecture, the World Trade Organization and numerous other multilateral agreements that make trade possible.54 The philosopher Thomas Pogge argues, for example, that world poverty is partly the result of the joint actions of 52 An attempt to interpret Greece’s debt as ‘odious debt’ is made in Bantekas and Vivien 2016, 539–565. In my view the argument cannot possibly succeed. Greece’s democratically elected governments created the debt mountain in the period between 1980 and 2010. 53 In this sense, we must consider the European Union to be an international and not a federal project. For this argument, see P. Eleftheriadis 2007, 1 and S. Weatherill 2016. 54 See, for example, J. Stiglitz 2002, where he describes the developments brought about by ‘global institutions’. See also D. Rodrik 2011. Jus Cogens (2020) 2:7–2718 developed states, which make it possible for dictators and corrupt politicians to siphon their ill- gotten gains to tax heavens around the world.55 The most extensive argument in this respect is offered by the American philosopher Aaron James. In his book, Fairness in Practice describes the process of creating institutions of international trade as an international ‘social practice’, a practice of ‘mutual reliance on common markets’ which, in his view, creates ‘a distinctive class of fairness responsibilities’.56 These responsibilities go beyond the explicit commitments of the parties. They are structural in that they require that the structures of international trade meet certain requirements of ‘structural equity’. James argues that the states that create these structures of international trade are jointly responsible for any harm and unfairness that such structures bring about. In James’ argument, the states’ negotiation has, in effect, the same effect as direct legislation.57 The states are structurally responsible for their processes of negotiation, just as much as if they were directly legislating the resulting consensus. What are the structural principles of fairness that bind the states, when they act in this way? For James, these principles require ‘due care’ for those who unfairly lose out from the system overall, principles of ‘fair distribution among states’ and ‘fair distribution within states’.58 The states that participate in the international social practice of trade are jointly responsible for setting up mechanisms for compensation to the losers of free trade, as well as mechanisms for maintaining equality in the distribution of benefits among states and among populations within states. An argument along these lines concerning structural responsibility is clearly applicable to the European Union, where the member states have legislated the terms of their own cooperation. They have created legally binding treaties and created enforcement mechanisms. Their actions have gone much beyond a mere ‘practice’ of international trade, as described by James. In the case of the European Union the structural responsibility of the states is even more direct than that of the creators of diffuse systems of cooperation, such as the World Trade Organization or systems of international arbitration. Cooperative structural fairness applies thus to the member states in two stages. At the first stage, which we may call ‘basic fairness’, the principle of fairness asks if an agreement to cooperate, given its formation and substantive content, is fair overall at the point the parties first enter it. This test requires, for example, that when the parties enter into some agreement to cooperate, they do so willingly and having been in a relatively even bargaining position to one another. The principle also assumes that, absent special circumstances, the cooperating parties would strike an agreement by which they would receive a fair return on their investment over time. Otherwise, the agreement might have been the result of exploitation or undue pressure. At a second stage, which we may call ‘fairness in practice’, the principle asks if the parties acted fairly as their agreement unfolded in practice. This aspect of fairness asks of the content of the respective obligations of the parties after the agreed rules are put into effect. John Rawls explains the relevance of fairness in practice in the following way. He says that fairness creates obligations on the participants in a mutually advantageous cooperative venture to continue to acquiesce by its terms.59 As Rawls puts it: ‘we are not to gain form the cooperative labors of 55 T. Pogge 2008, 97–123. For a powerful account of these processes by an investigative journalist, see O. Bullough 2018. 56 See A. James 2012, 131. 57 A. James 2012, 91–93. 58 A. James 2012, 203–245. 59 J. Rawls 1999a, 96. Rawls was also referring to H. L. A. Hart 1955, 185. Jus Cogens (2020) 2:7–27 19 others without doing our fair share’.60 This goes beyond the basic fairness that was in place at the original starting point. Whether we are fairly treated by others depends on how they treated us in the process of cooperation over time. Although some of the ongoing cooperation will be based on the original rules and commitments, the relevant obligations will also arise from the conduct, practices and expectations created and relied upon by others after the cooperative project started. So a cooperative project may be fair to begin with but can fail to remain fair because of the subsequently unreasonable conduct of one of the parties. 5 Basic Fairness I now turn to a fuller discussion of the idea of basic fairness in the interaction among states. My focus remains the framework of multiparty cooperation and principles of corrective justice. We are not asking about the ideal distribution of shares or about a certain ratio of return to investment. No such ratio of ‘fair return’ exists in the absence of a central distributing mechanism. The outcomes of any trade agreements are determined by economic practice, or in effect by a mixture of political judgement, prudent decision-making and, of course, chance. Because cooperative justice is a matter of bilateral relationship structured around the parties’ actions, what we are looking for is a standard of wrongness in bilateral relationships. What is fair and what is unfair in cooperation among states? Basic fairness rules out terms of cooperation that impose unjustified inequalities, or terms that are the result of unfair imposi- tion, monopolies, cartels and other competitive restrictions.61 Any such terms must be void and unenforceable. Can we organize these intuitive wrongs in a more coherent whole, so as to cover less obvious but still real unfairness? There are many ways in which we can interpret fairness in trade agreements. One set of was provided, as we saw above, by Aaron James with reference to the world trade order. James argues that the relation among states must be subject to a principle of ‘international relative gains’ according to which: ‘gains to each trading society, adjusted according to their respective national endowments (e.g. population size, resource base, level of development), are to be distributed equally, unless unequal gains flow (e.g., via special trade privileges) to poor countries’.62 Why should the gains be in principle equal? James argues that ‘the gains of trade are socially created, by the joint practice of market reliance’.63 This of course is the starting point for the responsibility of states, although not a sufficient reason for equal shares. He goes on to say: ‘Because each trading country has a morally relevant interest in greater rather than lesser national income gains, equal treatment requires equal distribution of gains, unless we can specify a relevant difference among participating countries’.64 James identifies two such ‘relevant’ differences as possible grounds for inequality of gain. First, relevant endowments of each country, such as population size, natural resources and degree of economic develop- ment. Second, ‘inequality of gain is fair if greater benefits flow to people who are worse off in absolute terms’.65 60 J. Rawls 1999a, 96. 61 See J. Rawls 1999b, 42–43. 62 A. James 2012, 203. 63 A. James 2012, 221. 64 Ibid. 65 A. James 2012, 222. Jus Cogens (2020) 2:7–2720 I find James’ arguments for equal shares and for requiring priority for the worse off unconvincing. What James recognizes as the ‘endowments’ exception cannot be limited only to the features he sets out. Other considerations are relevant too. The performance of a state in trading with other states does not depend only on the state structures but also on the success of private parties: producers, entrepreneurs and workers that produce relevant tradeable products that appeal to consumers abroad. Economic success or failure cannot therefore be imputed only to each state and its institutions. As long as the background terms of fair competition are respected, the outcome of economic competition will be the result of the ‘endowments’ that James describes as well as of the capacity – flexibility, agility and resourcefulness – of firms in producing competitive products and services. This is why James’ principle of equality in outcomes seems to me at odds with his general framework. He seems to leave out the element of uncertainty inherent in economic competition. If we allow for the effects of economic competition, equality of outcomes cannot be a default position. A second argument for fairness is provided by Andrea Sangiovanni, who has offered a sophisticated argument about fairness in trade specifically in the context of the European Union.66 Sangiovanni takes an ‘internationalist’ view on the justice that applies to the EU. He believes that the best argument for justice in the EU proceeds from the reciprocal commitments the states have made to each other. Sangiovanni argues that: ‘According to reciprocity-based internationalism, demands for social solidarity at all levels of governance can be understood as demands for a fair return in the mutual production of important collective goods’.67 Fair return is required because in effect the states have jointly produced the collective goods brought about by the European Union. Sangiovanni’s proposal is to ask what would be a rational insurance policy in case the member states considered the terms of their cooperation in advance of entering into this cooperative project. He asks ‘…what do member states and their citizens owe one other as a fair return for the mutual provision of these goods and the mutual exposure to these risks— goods and risks made possible by opening up their markets, societies and polities to the joint control and supervision of both supranational actors and intergovernmental decision-mak- ing?’68 The answer for Sangiovanni is that the fair return ‘which members states owe one another, under member state solidarity, is given by the level at which each state would insure against the potential losses identified above had they known the distribution of risks but not their place in the distribution’.69 Sangiovanni argues that by asking how states would have insured against the ‘risks intrinsic to the project of European integration, had they not known what state they would have turned out to be’, we eliminate the advantage at the bargaining table of the European social contract obtained by the fact that member states know their relative position – including their level of development, population size, welfare regime, type, etc.70 This argument is ambiguous, however. It is not clear if it proposes ‘fair shares’ as distributive shares, or a system of minimum insurance against failure. A question of what fair shares are appropriate is, as we have seen, a distributive question. It argues for an appropriate allocation among the various parties. Insurance is by contrast a corrective question. It is not an allocation of shares but a provision of redress. 66 A. Sangiovanni 2013, 1–29. 67 A. Sangiovanni 2013, 5. 68 A. Sangiovanni 2013, 17. 69 A. Sangiovanni 2013, 17–18. 70 A. Sangiovanni 2013, 18. Jus Cogens (2020) 2:7–27 21 It seems to me that the distinction between distribution and insurance is not clear in Sangiovanni’s argument. The aim of insurance is to provide reparation for some loss insured against. It is not the allocation of fair or equal, or less unequal, distributive shares, all things considered. On the one hand, he speaks of an argument from insurance, but on the other, he is also seeking fair shares. I believe that his argument needs amendment to make clear that what is relevant is a basic form of insurance and not a form of distribution. If we are seeking to model our fair background conditions of basic fairness on the basis of a hypothetical insurance scheme, we must envisage returns triggered by a type of wrongful action, not merely inequality in outcomes. The redress must correspond to the wrongful loss actually incurred, or loss in comparison to the position one would have been without the wrong. Here is how, I believe, the argument for basic fairness among states must be restated. Remember that the relevant principle is corrective justice as it applies to cooperative projects. It is one a principle of distributive shares. We proceed by identifying the threshold of wrongful conduct which generates a one-off claim for redress from one party to another, not a general pattern of fair distribution that should be imposed when it fails to materialize in real life. I propose the following formulation as the appropriate standard of background cooperative fairness in trading among states, which I call the ‘symmetry principle’: The Symmetry Principle: An agreement to cooperate for the purposes of international trade in goods and services is unfair and potentially unenforceable, if it is shown to create asymmetrical opportunities for gain and risks of loss for the parties involved, taking into account the parties’ original position, endowments and prospects as the agreement was reached. Following the principle of symmetry, a structure of cooperation will be unfair, if it creates asymmetrical opportunities for gain and risks of loss. The symmetry here refers both to the level of risk but also the gravity of the injury it may cause. Irreparable harms must be given much higher value than temporary harms. Similarly, permanent gains (e.g. those associated with education or long term health) are to be assessed differently from transient gains, economic or social. The principle of symmetrical risks tries thus to capture the idea proposed by Sangiovanni through the insurance approach. This is the thought that an agreement is fair if the parties would have been able to agree it as sufficiently beneficial to them, had they entered it without full knowledge of their circumstances.71 The idea of symmetry of risks seeks to reflect the idea of reciprocity for states that are greatly unequal in size and economic size. Reciprocity entails a form of insurance for all parties: we ask what costs the member states would be willing to pay to offset the risks generated by the project of cooperation.72 There are also similarities here with a principle that Aaron James discusses by the name of principle of ‘reciprocity of risk’, which he eventually rejects. 73 James’ idea involves only risk of loss, not opportunity for gain. Yet, his account of reciprocity is the same idea as that behind the ‘symmetry principle’. One of the reasons he gives for rejecting the ‘reciprocity of risk’ 71 An analogy may be made between this argument and Rawls’ argument for the making of a constitution in a constitutional convention, in the Theory of Justice. This stage of law-making, for Rawls, was the second of a ‘four stage sequence’ where the parties were aware of their individual circumstances (whereas they were not in the ‘original position’ concerning the basic structure. 72 The logic of an insurance calculation is the same as set out by A. Sangiovanni 2013, 18. 73 A. James 2012, 233–237. Jus Cogens (2020) 2:7–2722 principle is that ‘current trade practice is clearly a situation of non-reciprocal risk’. This, however, is not a reason to reject the principle. He also notes that symmetry of risks is compatible with terrible losses for both sides, if they are symmetrical.74 This argument fails, however, for another reason. If a cooperative agreement is open to massive losses of the kind that James has in mind, it will not be struck at all, at least not if we rule out imposition, deception and the like. The underlying idea behind the symmetry principle is a requirement of reciprocity. In the philosophical literature, reciprocity commonly refers to the requirement that one returns a benefit they have received from another.75 In his defence of reciprocity as an ideal of private law, Arthur Ripstein introduces it as follows: ‘The root idea, fundamental to both fair terms of interaction and the idea of responsibility, is one of reciprocity, the idea that one person may not unilaterally set the terms of his interactions with others’.76 This is a distinct matter from that of keeping a promise. A promise or an exchange of promises creates obligations by virtue of itself alone. Reciprocity creates obligations by virtue of rendering a benefit to another, irrespective of a promise. The economist Serge-Christophe Kolm, for example, begins his wide-ranging study of reciprocity with a definition that stresses that reciprocity goes beyond a ‘binding exchange agreement’.77 Reciprocity applies beyond agreements, when, for example, no agreement exists or the one that exists has failed to meet a fair measure of equal return among the parties. In those cases, the reason to offer something – or the motivation– is independent of any promise or other undertaking. Some key examples Kolm discusses, for example, are the reciprocity of giving and receiving gifts or reciprocity in family relations. Philosophers today deploy reciprocity as a political ideal when they discuss the design of a social contract or give a similar egalitarian basis for social life. John Rawls, for example, explicitly discussed reciprocity alongside legitimacy. He links the idea of a reasonable person with a recognition of the value of reciprocity as follows: ‘Reasonable persons [are moved by a desire for] a social world in which they, as free and equal, can cooperate with others on terms all can accept. They insist that reciprocity should hold within that world so that each benefits along with others’.78 In light of the disagreements, we expect to have with others about the terms of cooperation, legitimate political power of one person over another requires that: ‘our exercise of political power is fully proper only when it is exercised in accordance with a constitution the essentials of which all citizens as free and equal may reasonably be expected to endorse in the light of principles and ideals acceptable to their common human reason’.79 For this view, political power must fulfil a criterion of reciprocity, in that citizens must reasonably believe that all can reasonably accept a particular set of institutions. Reciprocity is therefore at the heart of corrective justice. As Aristotle put it, voluntary exchanges or instances of cooperation raise issues of corrective justice regarding voluntary transactions.80 For Aristotle, justice in voluntary transactions involves not simply keeping their parties to their word by way 74 A. James 2012, 235. 75 See J. Rawls 1999c, 190. 76 A. Ripstein 1999, 2. 77 ‘Reciprocity is treating other people as other people treat you voluntarily and not as a result of a binding exchange agreement’; S. C. Kolm 2008, 1. 78 J. Rawls 1993, 50. 79 J. Rawls 1993, 137. 80 Aristotle 1926, 273, (‘διορθωτικόν δίκαιον, εν τοις συναλλάγμασι τοις εκουσίοις’). Jus Cogens (2020) 2:7–27 23 of a formal equality – as in a simple commercial contract – but at the same time by being willing to preserve proportionate equality in the fruits of joint activity or cooperation.81 6 Conclusion When the European Monetary Union was first proposed, it hoped that the common currency would create conditions of economic and political convergence among the member states.82 Looking back, it is clear that this aim has not been achieved. The Eurozone today is fragmented between states of the ‘core’ that have low unemployment, high rates of investment and healthy growth and states of the ‘periphery’, which have high unemployment – especially among the young – low levels of savings and investment and very low rates of growth. Some of the most distinguished commentators have linked this failure to the Eurozone’s original design. 83 The American economist Kenneth Rogoff, who has co-authored one of the leading studies of financial crises,84 has given a categorical rejection of the Eurozone’s design. He has said that ‘the problem at the heart of the euro crisis’ is that ‘the eurozone is a half-built house’ and that ‘it was a catastrophic mistake to put monetary union ahead of fiscal and political union’.85 The absence of central fiscal policy, for Rogoff, meant that European policy makers did not have the tools to address the crisis. He concluded: ‘Monetary policy is simply one side of fiscal policy. Monetary union without fiscal union is an accident waiting to happen’.86 Similarly, the distinguished economist C. Fred Bergsten wrote that ‘the European crisis is rooted in a failure of institutional design’ and that ‘the absence of crucial policy tools constrained Europe’s ability to reach a solution quickly, triggering severe market reactions that continue to this day’.87 If these economists are right, then there is a clear case of ‘structural responsibility’ burdening all the original members of the Eurozone. They must all be held responsible for creating an economic practice with potentially disastrous consequences for some of them. Twenty years after the Euro came to being, the economies of Greece, Italy and Spain are now caught in a vicious circle of low growth, high indebtedness and high unemployment.88 These states cannot now leave the Euro without running even more serious risks of economic collapse, which would set back their own economic recovery even further. This is a loss that demands redress, if it has been caused by an unfairly burdening overall structure. If we accept these leading economists’ arguments, we can see that the financial assistance programmes were at least part of a required redress for unfairness. Given that the crisis had systemic roots in a collective failure, the rescue operations can be seen as the appropriate moral response. Since the loss was caused by the design of the cooperative project, the principle of structural responsibility must take effect. The programmes 81 Aristotle 1926, 8. 82 The main case for the Euro had been made in the European Commission’s paper, One Market: One Money; An evaluation of the potential benefits and costs of forming an economic and monetary union, 1990. For the history of the creation of the EMU see H. James 2014. 83 See the thorough analysis by Franks et al. 2018. 84 Reinhart and Rogoff 2009. 85 K. S. Rogoff 2018. 86 K. S. Rogoff 2018. 87 C. F. Bergsten 2012, 216. For similar views on the structural nature of the Eurozone’s failings, see Moravcsik 2012, 54–68 and J. Pisani-Ferry 2014. 88 For a telling summary of the Eurozone’s division between North and South, see D. Ball 2018. Jus Cogens (2020) 2:7–2724 are manifestations of morally required solidarity under a symmetry principle: they compen- sated the burdened member states for the loss caused by the structural flaws of the Eurozone’s design (although they, arguably, also took into account those member states’ own contributory culpability in not doing enough to avoid the worst aspects of the crisis during the boom years). If this argument is correct, then the financial assistance programmes were not merely exercises in self-preservation and economic prudence. They were also expressions of a new form of solidarity generated by the economic cooperation of European states under common principles of corrective justice. Acknowledgements This paper was written while I was a visiting research fellow at the Bank of Greece in 2017–2018. I am very grateful to Heather Gibson, Christina Tsochatzi, Christos Hadjiemmanuil, Dimitris Malliaropoulos and the research team at the Bank of Greece for their extremely valuable assistance, comments and discussions, including at a series of three seminars, which I gave there. I am also very grateful to Menelaos Markakis and Michalis Ioannidis for their very useful comments on an earlier draft. Open Access This article is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License, which permits use, sharing, adaptation, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, as long as you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the source, provide a link to the Creative Commons licence, and indicate if changes were made. The images or other third party material in this article are included in the article's Creative Commons licence, unless indicated otherwise in a credit line to the material. If material is not included in the article's Creative Commons licence and your intended use is not permitted by statutory regulation or exceeds the permitted use, you will need to obtain permission directly from the copyright holder. To view a copy of this licence, visit http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/. References Alexy R (2009) The argument from injustice: a reply to legal positivism. Oxford University Press, Oxford Aristotle (1926) Nicomachean Ethics, H. Rackham (trans.). Loeb Library, Harvard University Press, Cambridge Ball D (2018) Aftereffects of Eurozone Crisis Plague Europe’s South’ Wall Street Journal, available at: https://www.wsj.com/articles/aftereffects-of-eurozone-crisis-plague-europes-south-1527879732. Accessed 01 Oct 2019 Bantekas I, Vivien R (2016) On the odiousness of Greek debt. Eur Law J 22(4):539–565 Bergsten CF (2012) Why the Euro will survive, Foreign Affairs, available at: https://www.foreignaffairs. com/articles/europe/2012-09-01/why-euro-will-survive. Accessed 01 Oct 2019 Bjorge E (2015) The Vienna rules, evolutionary interpretation, and the intentions of the parties. In: Bianchi A, Peat D, Windsor M (eds) Interpretation in international law. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 342–347 Browne J, Johnson P, Phillips D (2016) The budget of the European Union: a guide: IFS briefing note BN181. Institute of Fiscal Studies, London Brunnermeier MK, James H, Landau J-P (eds) (2016) The euro and the battle of ideas. Princeton University Press, Princeton Bullough O (2018) Moneyland: why thieves and crooks now rule the world and how to take it Back. Profile Book, London Campos T (2017) The global health crisis: ethical responsibilities. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge de Búrca G (2005) Towards European welfare? In: de Búrca G (ed) EU law, and the welfare state: in search of solidarity. Oxford University Press, Oxford de Witte F (2008) Justice in the EU: The Emergence of Transnational Solidarity. Oxford University Press, Oxford di Fabio U (2014) Karlsruhe makes a Referral. Ger Law J 15:107–110 Dorr O, Schmalenbach K (eds) (2011) Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties. Springer, Berlin Dworkin R (1986) Law’s Empire. Harvard University Press, Cambridge Eleftheriadis P (2007) The Idea of a European Constitution. Oxf J Leg Stud 27(1):1–21 Englard I (2009) Corrective and Distributive Justice: From Aristotle to Modern Times. Oxford University Press, Oxford Jus Cogens (2020) 2:7–27 25 https://www.wsj.com/articles/aftereffects-of-eurozone-crisis-plague-europes-south-1527879732 https://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/europe/2012-09-01/why-euro-will-survive https://www.foreignaffairs.com/articles/europe/2012-09-01/why-euro-will-survive European Commission (1990) One Market: One Money; An evaluation of the potential benefits and costs of forming an economic and monetary union, available at: https://ec.europa.eu/info/business-economy- euro/economy-finance-and-euro-publications_en. Accessed 01 Oct 2019 Fabbrini F (2016) Economic governance in Europe: comparative paradoxes and constitutional challenges. Oxford University Press, Oxford Forst R (2015) Justice, democracy and the right to justification: reflections on Jürgen Neyer’s normative theory of the European Union. In: Kochenov D, de Búrca G, Williams A (eds) Europe’s Justice Deficit? Hart Publishing, London, pp 227–234 Franks J, Barkbu B, Blavy R, Oman W, Schoelerman H (2018) Economic convergence in the Euro area: coming together or drifting apart? In: IMF Working Paper, 18/10. International Monetary Fund, Washington, DC Habermas J (2013) The crisis of the European Union: a response. Polity Press, Cambridge Habermas J (2015a) Democracy, solidarity, and the European crisis. In: van Middelaar L, van Parijs P (eds) After the Storm: How to Save Democracy in Europe. Lannoo, Tielt Habermas J (2015b) The lure of technocracy. Polity Press, Cambridge Hart, H. L. A. (1955). Are there any natural rights? Philosophical Review 64 (2):175-191. Herman B (1984) Mutual aid and respect for persons. Ethics 94(4):577–602 Herman B (2012) Being helped and being grateful: imperfect duties, the ethics of possession, and the unity of morality. J Philos 109(5–6):391–411 Hinarejos A (2015) The Euro area crisis in constitutional perspective. Oxford University Press, Oxford, Oxford Howse R (2007) The concept of odious debt in public international law: UNCTAD Discussion Papers, No. 185. United Nations, New York James A (2012) Fairness in Practice: A Social Contract for a Global Economy. Oxford University Press, Oxford Joerges C (2017) Social justice in an ever more diverse union. In: Vandenbroucke F, Barnard C, de Baere G (eds) A European Social Union after the Crisis. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 92–119 King J (2016) The Doctrine of Odious Debt in International Law: A Restatement. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Kolm SC (2008) Reciprocity: An Economics of Social Relations. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Küçük E (2016) Solidarity in EU law: an elusive political statement or a legal principle with substance? Maastricht Journal of European and Comparative Law 23:965–983 Mody A (2018) Eurotragedy: A Drama in Nine Acts. Oxford University Press, Oxford Moravcsik A (2012) Europe after the crisis: how to sustain a common currency. Foreign Aff 91(3):54–68 Nagel T (2005) The problem of global justice. Philos Public Aff 33(2):113–147 Neyer J (2012) The justification of Europe: a political theory of supranational integration. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 35–55 Neyer J (2015) Justice and the right to justification: conceptual reflections. In: Kochenov D, de Búrca G, Williams A (eds) Europe’s Justice Deficit? Hart, Oxford, pp 211–226 O’Leary S (2005) Solidarity and citizenship rights in the charter of fundamental rights of the European Union. In: De Burca G (ed) EU Law, and the Welfare State: In Search of Solidarity. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 39–87 Pisani-Ferry J (2014) The Euro Crisis and its Aftermath. Oxford University Press, Oxford Pogge T (2008) World Poverty and Human Rights: Cosmopolitan Responsibilities and Reforms, 2nd edn. Polity, Cambridge Rawls J (1993) Political Liberalism. Columbia University Press, New York Rawls J (1999a) A Theory of Justice, Revised edn. The Belknap Press Harvard University, Cambridge Rawls J (1999b) The Law of Peoples. Harvard University Press, Cambridge Rawls J (1999c) Justice as Reciprocity. In: Rawls J, Freeman S (eds) Collected Papers. Harvard University Press, Cambridge Reinhart CM, Rogoff KS (2009) This Time is Different: Eight Centuries of Financial Folly. Princeton University Press, Princeton Ripstein A (1999) Equality, Responsibility, and the Law. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Rodrik D (2011) The Globalization Paradox. Oxford University Press, Oxford Rogoff KS (2018) Crash Time, Project Syndicate, available at: https://www.project-syndicate.org/onpoint/crash- time-by-kenneth-rogoff-2018-09?barrier=accesspaylog Ross M (2010) Solidarity – a new constitutional paradigm for the EU? In: Ross M, Borgmann-Prebil Y (eds) Promoting Solidarity in the European Union. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 23–45 Sangiovanni, Andrea (2013). Solidarity in the European Union. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 33 (2):213-241. Scharpf FW (2002) The European social model: coping with the challenges of diversity’. J Common Mark Stud 40:645–670 Simmonds NE (2007) Law as a Moral Idea. Oxford University Press, Oxford Sinn HW (2014) The Euro Trap: On Bursting Bubbles, Budgets, and Beliefs. Oxford University Press, Oxford Jus Cogens (2020) 2:7–2726 https://ec.europa.eu/info/business-economy-euro/economy-finance-and-euro-publications_en https://ec.europa.eu/info/business-economy-euro/economy-finance-and-euro-publications_en https://www.project-syndicate.org/onpoint/crash-time-by-kenneth-rogoff-2018-09?barrier=accesspaylog https://www.project-syndicate.org/onpoint/crash-time-by-kenneth-rogoff-2018-09?barrier=accesspaylog Somek A (2015) The Preoccupation with Rights and the Embrace of Inclusion: A Critique. In: Kochenov D, de Búrca G, Williams A (eds) Europe’s Justice Deficit? Hart, Oxford, pp 295–310 Stiglitz J (2002) Globalization and its Discontents. Penguin, London Stiglitz JE (2016) The Euro: How a Common Currency Threatens the Future of Europe. New Norton, New York Summers RS (2000) The Conceptualization of Good Faith in American Contract Law. In: Zimmermann R, Whittaker S (eds) Good Faith in European Contract Law. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 118–144 Tuori K, Tuori K (2014) The Eurozone Crisis: A Constitutional Analysis. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge United Nations (2002) Decision regarding delimitation of the border between Eritrea and Ethiopia, XXV Reports of International Arbitral Awards, available at: https://legal.un.org/riaa/cases/vol_XXV/83-195.pdf. Accessed 15 Sept 2019 Vandenbroucke F (2017) The Idea of a European Social Union: A Normative Introduction. In: Vandenbroucke F, Barnard C, de Baere G (eds) A European Social Union after the Crisis. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 3–46 Walker N (2015) Justice in and of the European Union. In: Kochenov D, de Búrca G, Williams A (eds) Europe’s Justice Deficit? Hart, Oxford, pp 247–258 Weatherill S (2016) Law and Values in the European Union. Oxford University Press, Oxford Weinrib EJ (2012) Corrective Justice. Oxford University Press, Oxford Williams A (2010) The Ethos of Europe: Values, Law and Justice in the EU. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge Jus Cogens (2020) 2:7–27 27 https://legal.un.org/riaa/cases/vol_XXV/83-195.pdf Corrective Justice Among States Abstract From Fairness to Solidarity Distributive Claims Distributive and Corrective Justice Structural Responsibility Basic Fairness Conclusion References work_lb46hwppbbf45h7lo42envssky ---- DOCUMENT RESUME ED 351 222 SO 022 322 AUTHOR Connell, R. W. TITLE Citizenship, Social Justice & Curriculum. PUB DATE 92 NOTE 19p.; Paper presented at the International Conference on Sociology of Education (Westhill, United Kingdom, January, 1992). PUB TYPE Information Analyses (070) Speeches/Conference Papers (150) EDRS PRICE MF01/PC01 Plus Postage. DESCRIPTORS Access to Education; *Citizenship; Citizenship Education; Comparative Education; Developed Nations; Educational Philosophy; Educational Policy; Educational Sociology; *Educational Theories; *Elementary School Curriculum; Elementary Secondary Education; *Equal Education; Foreign Countries; International Education; *Justice; *Secondary School Curriculum; Social Theories; Social Values IDENTIFIERS *Australia ABSTRACT Equal access to education is not enough to guarantee that all students are receiving the same quality education. Curricular knowledge does not exist value-free; it is affected by the context in which it exists--with teachers, school officials, syllabus committees, and education policymakers, among others, influencing the social process through which students are educated. This paper is concerned with social justice in education, and contends that the curriculum and teachers' work should be given central roles in bringing it about. A model of curricular justice that is based on three priaciples is proposed. First, in order to prepare all citizens for participation in democracies, social justice requires that a common curricula must be provided to all students. Such an education ideally would involve ungraded and cooperative learning practices in respect to the common curriculum. Second, since the current curriculum embodies the interests of the most advantaged, social justice requires a "counter-hegemonic" curriculum, designed to embody the interests and perspectives of the least advantaged. The third criterion involves the recognition that as well as imparting knowledge, educators engage in a process of producing and reproducing social relationships. This means that "equality" cannot be static; it is always being produced or reproduced in greater or lesser degrees. This criterion of curricular justice involves producing educational strategies that produce greater equality in the whole set of social relationships to which the educational system is linked. A list of 34 references is included. (DB) *********************************************************************** Reproductions supplied by EDRS are the best that can be made from the original document. *********************************************************************** IP; CITIZENSHIP, SOCIAL JUSTICE & CURRICULUM . Paper to International Conference on Sociology of Education, Westhill, January 1992 R.W. Connell Professor of Australian Studies, Harvard University 560 William James Hall 33 Kirkland St., Cambridge, MA 02138, USA BEST COPY MIME U.S. DEPARTMENT OF EDUCATION Office of Educational Research and improvement EDUCATIONAL RESOURCES INFORMATION CENTER (ERIC) T is document has been reproduced as owed from the person or organization originating it C Minor Changes have been made to improve reproduction quality Points of view or opinions stated in this docu- ment do not necessarily represent official OERI position or policy "PERMISSION TO REPRODUCE THIS M ERIAL HAS BEEN GRANTED BY Al& TO THE EDUCATIONAL RESOURCES INFORMATION CENTER (ERIC)." 2 Introduction The idea of 'citizenship' everywhere has two faces, and nowhere are they more sharply contrasted than in education. On the one hand citizenship appears as a principle of regulation and social control, casting citizens into standardized relations of obedience and orderliness. One sees children at the start of the day in North American schools, eyes fixed on the flag, hands over hearts, reciting a 'pledge of allegiance' which is written to sound like a legal or religious declaration. On the other hand citizenship appears as a claim of rights, as a demand by the excluded for access and participation. So one sees an adult literacy class of agricultural workers in the Brazilian north-east, the educational process being an essential step towards their economic and political advance. In the United States at present there is controversy about transferring funds from school districts serving the wealthy to school districts serving the poor. The 'Robin Hood' policy would not have got off the ground at all without a concept of citizenship to legitimate the claim for equal treatment. In this paper I will be exploring the second face of citizenship, the claim for social justice in education. I will argue that the way the issue is commonly treated misses what is specifically educational about education, and fails to deal with the main way inequality is produced in Western education systems--through curriculum effects. I will mainly use examples from Australian education, that being the system I have studied most; but the argument applies to all Western educational systems in affluent capitalist countries (and to parallel processes in other contexts). `Social justice and education' as a distributive question Questions about 'education and justice' are not new. In the Western philosophical tradition the first great treatise on education, Plato's Republic, was also the first great treatise on justice. In neo-Confucian China, the legitimacy of the scholar-official system of government flowed from open selection to the elite by literary exams. But we would hardly rest our current ideal of education on elite concepts like Plato's guardians or Confucian mandarins. In modern discussions the issue of 'education and justice' has 3 3 been framed in another way. Debates centre on the service provided to the whole population by a mass education system, and are posed as questions of distributive justice. Questions of 'distributive justice' are questions about who gets what--particularly, who gets how much of some social good. The most familiar 'social good' is money, and the distribution of wealth and income is much debated. For instance, recent research estimates that the richest 5% of Australians own about 50% of the total private wealth, and such figures always raise argument as to whether too much wealth is concentrated in too few hands. That is the classic form of an argument about distributive justice: do some people have too much, others too little? As Walzer (1983) has shown, distributive questions can be raised about a whole series of `social goods': money, welfare, office, leisure, love, grace, recognition--and education. (In what follows, I use the term 'justice' in the sense of Walzer and of Rawls (1971), as a question of fairness in distribution for which the normal criterion is equality. There is another common usage of 'justice' in which it refers to getting what one deserves--for instance in `criminal justice', or 'wage justice'. For the case of social justice in education, the two usages converge. 'Deserts' of individuals may differ markedly, as the criminal law presumes; but it is difficult to see how a whole social group can deserve either more or less education than another social group; so this conception too points to equality. But there is a risk, in emphasising equality in distribution, that it will be seen only as a matter of individual rights. So I confess also to a touch of Platonism, and emphasise that individual equality is the condition, not the goal, of a just social order. The quality of our collective life is central to the argument.) Over the last 150 years or so, in 'Western' and Western-influenced societies, questions of justice in education have mainly been about access to formal schooling and certification. The 150 years is, roughly, the life-span of state-funded, bureaucratically-controlled mass elementary school systems. Mass elementary schooling has everywhere coexisted with a much more selective (sometimes private) provision of secondary and higher education. Out of this history came two great questions of distributive justice. The :first was whether to provide elementary education for the whole population (an issue now settled in countries like Australia, far from settled in countries like India). The second was about fair access to the selective upper levels of formal education. Secondary schooling was the focus of this issue in industrialised countries for most of this century, but now higher education increasingly is the 4 focus. We see debates hotting up about university enrolments and overall funding--that is, how much access there shall be; and about university fees and rich students buying university places- that is, about who shall have access. These distributive questions underlie the two great enterprises in educational justice that have been undertaken in the last generation. On a world scale, justice is pursued by the creation of universal elementary school systems, and the attempt at universal literacy, in poor countries. In affluent countries like the United States, Britain and Australia, the attempt is made to establish `equal opportunity' in education via scholarships, compensatory education, desegregation, affirmative action, Assisted Places shemes, etc. In Australia the Disadvantaged Schools Program is the best known example of this attempt (Connell, White and Johnston, 1991). Both of these enterprises generally take the content and form of education for granted. The 'social good' they seek to distribute is the educational service provided by bureaucratically- controlled mass schooling systems of the type created in Europe and North America in the mid 19th century. The debates about justice are about who gets how much of this service (as measured, for instance, by that staple variable in survey research, 'years of education'). What the service is, is debated in a separate theatre altogether - -the, theatre of curriculum theory, teaching method and the psychology of learning. This becomes very clear when education authorities make explicit statements about their efforts on behalf of the disadvantaged. In the late 1980s the Australian Labor Party, faced with an increasingly disillusioned rank-and-file, sought to formulate a 'social justice' policy. Education was included in the resulting policy statements, which are important as the clearest recent formulations of the issue of justice in Australian education. A careful look at these documents shows that they remain within the distributive framework. Here, for instance, is the 'overall objective' of equity policy in higher education as formulated in A Fair Chance For All: To ensure that Australians from all groups in society have the opportunity to participate successfully in higher education. This will be achieved by changing the balance of the student population to reflect more closely the composition of society as a whole. (Department of Employment, Education and Training, 1990) Such statements raise scarcely any questions about what kind of education is being provided; that is taken for granted. The issue they address is who gets how much of the familiar product. 5 Distrilxtion and content The underlying weakness of this approach to educational justice is its indifference to the nature of education itself. For education is a social process in which the 'how much' cannot be separated from the 'what'. There is an inescapable link between distribution and content. I learnt this in the research for M&IgtheDilfeitse.Difference (Connell, Ashenden, Kessler and Dowsett, 1982). Starting from the idea that the unequal distribution of education between social classes had to do with differences between working-class and ruling-class families, we found this was so only because they had different relationships with a particular kind of curriculum. The hegemonic curriculum in Australian high schools has a class history embedded in it, and operates to include and exclude students on class lines. Broadly similar conclusions were being reached on the basis of research in France, the United States, Britain and Canadq (cf. Whiny 1985). It follows that justice cannot be achieved by distributing the same amount of this standard good to children of all social classes. Education is not an object, like a bag of wheat or a computer; it is a human social relationship. That 'good' means different things to ruling-class and working-class children, and will do different things for them (or to them). This is a crucial point, and one where the argument often stalls. Surely knowledge is knowledge, science is science, great literature is great literature--and the school (on behalf of the society) wants children to acquire them? To understand the problem, we must look at where curricular knowledge comes from. The case of natural science is instructive. As Kuhn (1970) and other historians and sociologists of science have shown, scientific knowledge does not exist as isolated facts, and is not produced by isolated geniuses struck by wandering apples. Scientific knowledge comes in large chunks- paradigms, disciplines, theories, research programs, etc.--and is produced in a highly organised social process. Research communities, research institutions, communications networks, are the vital social mileux for scientific knowledge to be produced. These social milieux are located in social structures, and are necessarily shaped by them. There is a powerful (though complex) link between the rise of modern physical science and the rise of modern capitalism. Some fascinating recent research has shown there is also a link with gender (Harding 1986, Keller 1985, Merchant 1983). Western physical sciences were constructed specifically by men, through practices and understandings reflecting men's dominant place in the 6 social and natural world. In areas like medical science this involved a conscious, and largely successful, attack on healing practices and understandings of health associated with women. Once produced, knowledge still has to be selected or compiled to make a curriculum. This too is a social process, it is not done in heaven by a committee of epistemological angels. Another fascinating body of historical research has traced the creation of school 'subjects' like `geography' by inquiries, syllabus committees, academic entrepreneurs, and bureaucrats (Goodson 1985, 1988). Research has traced struggles for space in the schools' offerings, struggles over prestige and dominance for particular bodies of knowledge. Herbert Spencer's 1859 essay 'What Knowledge is of Most Worth?', arguing the case for natural science against classics, is one of the great moments in this struggle. Taken-for-granted ideas about what are `basic skills', what are the `core' areas of knowledge, how knowledge itself is divided, are all the products of an intricate politics shaped by the wider distribution of social power. Once compiled, curriculum knowledge does not float about the school as a kind of academic ectoplasm. It is a curriculum only so far -.s it is embodied in the school's educational practices. Curriculum is not only a statement of what is to be learnt by the students, it is also a definition of the teacher's work--it describes a labour process (Connell 1985, AppleVig ). It is therefore unavoidably shaped by the organisational and industrial imperatives of the school and school system, and by the occupational and professional needs of teachers as a workforce. A key product of these imperatives is a system of assessment and educational selection. The importance of assessment in controlling and shaping curriculum knowledge is historically shown in the role of matriculation-level examinations, from the Leaving Certificate to the Higher School Certificate, in shaping Australian secondary education as a whole (Clarke 1987, 1990; WF Connell 1991). It is currently shown by the importance that conservatives in the United States, up to and including President Bush, attach to the installation of a national standardized testing system as a means of control over schools. Assessment systems are potent because they shape the form of the curriculum as well as its more obvious content. An individualized, competitive assessment system shapes learning as the individual appropriation of reproducible items of knowledge and the individual cultivation of skills. This has important consequences for justice. Such a conception of learning produces, as 7 a cultural effect, a belief in the unequal educational merit of individual students--as, for a wide variety of reasons, their appropriation of knowledges and cultivation of skills proceeds at different paces and along different paths. In turn the conception of unequal merit (intelligence, learning capacity, talent, diligence, educability, achievement--there are innumerable variants on the idea) validates unequal offers of education. Streaming, tracking, talented child programs, selection for university, scholarships, honour!. programs, selective high schools, assisted places schemes, accelerated promotion--indeed most of the affronts to substantive equality of provision in public schooling--are routinely justified by the notions of unequal merit which are generated by the competitive academic curriculum and its individualized competitive assessment system. This justification is now so routine that we see the astonishing spectacle of educational 'reformers' claiming that 'talented children' (most of whom come from advantaged social groups) are among the disadvantaged unless they get a special deal which will increase their advantages. Here the social agenda embedded in a particular curriculum form has suddenly become visible. It is also highly visible where the curriculum is exotic and new. In many third-world countries the importation of Western education, centered on the familiar academic curriculum and individualized assessment, has resulted in severe struggles for educational advantage. And in every part of the world where the social consequences have been investigated, class inequalities are found (see eg. Foster 1980). The issues are global in scale. Curricular justice: three principles These facts about education systems require us to re-think 'social justice in education' in ways that give a central place to curriculum, and thus to teachers' work. We need an account of what might be called curricular justice. Such a concept, based on the way social effects are embedded in the curriculum-as-practised, would give us guidelines for building-in considerations of justice while making and remaking curricula. I wish to suggest three principles that, taken together, might constitute a model of curricular justice. (1) Participation and common schooling. School systems commonly claim, in statements 8 of goals, to be preparing future citizens for participation in a democracy. Thus the Australian Education Council, the ministers of education in Australian state and federal governments, included in their recent declaration of ten 'National Goals' for Schooling in Australia: To develop knowledge, skills, attitudes and values which will enable students to participate as active and informed citizens in our democratic Australian society within an international context. (Australian Education Council 1989) If we take this purpose seriously, it has major implications for curriculum. The notion of `democracy' implies collective decision-making on major issues in which all citizens have, in principle, an equal voice. Major issues in modern states include war and peace, investment, employment policy, urban development and environmental protection, sexual violence, social welfare provision, the content of mass communication, and the design of education systems. To be active participants in such decision - making requires a range of knowledge and skills (including the skill of getting more knowledge). This range is required for all citizens, as Walzer forcefully argues. You cannot have a democracy in which some 'citizens' only receive decisions made by others. That is why feminists are right in pointing out that a society in which men routinely exert control over women is no democracy (for the history of this issue see Pateman 1988). Here then is the basis of a common curriculum which must be provided to all students as a matter of social justice. This is a much stronger criterion than the invocations of 'democracy' in Corporate Goals imply. This criterion rules out all selection, competitive assessment, streaming and classifying mechanisms in schooling while the common curriculum is in operation, since such mechanisms would tend to differentiate content and therefore advantage some citizens over others. It points, rather, to ungraded and cooperative learning practices in respect of the common curriculum. They should be cooperative, since all participating citizens are advantaged (as citizens of a democracy) by each others' learning. In this respect, justice would be significantly advanced by banning all grading and competitive testing during the compulsory years of schooling. Since a necessary part of the knowledge and skills of participants in democracy is an understanding of the cultures and in%!.rests of the other pa,tcipants, this criterion also rules out curricula produced from a single socially-dominant standpoint. It points firmly towards the 9 principle of the 'inclusive curriculum' proposed by Blackburn and others (1985): curricula which include and validate the experiences of women as well as men, Aborigines as well as whites, workers as well as professionals. The attempt to produce a 'diverse' or 'multicultural' curriculum in the United States, currently resisted by conservatives with rhetoric against 'political correctness', is clearly supported by this principle. (2) The interests of the least advantaged. Rawls in A Theory of Justice (1971) proposes that education must specifically serve the interests of the 'least favoured' groups in society., The principle of advantaging the least advantaged is central in Rawls' general theory, and captures what is usually meant in public politics by talk of 'social justice', even in the limited sense of Social Justice policy statements. This principle too has strong implications for curriculum. They become clear when we think about the social history of curriculum and the way the current hegemonic curriculum embodies the interests of the most advantaged. Justice requires a counter-hegemonic curriculum, designed to embody the interests and perspectives of the least advantaged. What this might mean concretely is being worked out by teachers in a variety of settings: the Disadvantaged Schools Program, multicultural education, programs for girls, Aboriginal education, certain adult literacy programs. In this paper I can only gesture towards this important work and make two general points about it. First, social justice is not satisfied by curriculum ghettos. Separate-and-different curricula have some attractions, but leave the currently hegemonic curriculum in place. Social justice requires moving out from the starting-point to reconstruct the mainstream to embody the interests of the least advantaged in a generalized way. (For the logic of counter-hegemonic curriculum, see Connell 1988). Second, social justice is not satisfied with one counter-hegemonic project. Contemporary social science recognises, as contemporary social practice does, a number of major patterns of inequality: gender, class, race, ethnicity, and (on a world scale) nationality. Curricular justice requires counter-hegemonic projects across this whole spectrum. In practice there will be great diversity in what is undertaken. I am not trying to lay down a blueprint here, but to indicate the scope of the principle of curricular justice. No institutionalized pattern of social inequality is in 10 principle exempted from it. To recognise that knowledge can be organised differently, and that different ways of constructing it will advantage and disadvantage different groups, is to risk falling into relativism. There have been education systems where the political outcome is the key criterion for curriculum choice. It is important to avoid this, as it would abandon the element of independent truth in, for instance, scientific accounts of the world; and therefore the possibility of critique of the political agenda itself. (To notice that these accounts are shaped by gender and class is not to say that gender and class is their only content; they also document an encounter of a gender-and-class- shaped consciousness with the natural world.) The principle of the interests of the least advantaged provides a clear motive for avoiding relativism, since it cannot be in their interest to continue being excluded from that knowledge of the natural world that is embodied in conventional science. A counter-hegemonic curriculum must include the generalisable part of the conventional curriculum, guaranteeing all students access (hopefully, critical access) to scientific methods and findings. (3) The historical production of equality. There seems to be a contradiction between the criterion of participant citizenship, requiring common curriculum, and the principle of pursuing the interests of specific groups, the least advantaged. This could logically be resolved by using one of Rawls' devices and introducing a 'lexical ordering' of the principles of curricular justice. Thus we might say that participation has priority, and the criterion of the least advantaged applies after the participation criterion is satisfied. This would rapidly lead to educational absurdity. It would assume the curriculum can be partitioned into 'participant citizenship' and 'counter- hegemonic' bits, a distinction that is impossible to maintain in the realties of teachers' daily work in schools. If a counter-hegemonic criterion is to be practically useful it must apply to the same educational processes that the participant citizenship criterion applies to, and we must find a way to think these criteria together. The tension between them can be handled (though not eliminated) if we take note of the historical character of the social structures producing inequality. Their `existence' is not that of objects like stones or planets, but is a process of producing and reproducing social relationships. 1 1 This means that 'equality' cannot be static; it is always being produced in greater or lesser degrees. We must think of the social effects of curriculum as the historical production of more (or, as the case may be, less) equality. Participant citizenship and counter-hegemonic criteria can now be seen as elements in the same historical process; we deal with the tension between them in making strategic judgments about how to advance equality. The criterion of curricular justice is the tendency of an educational strategy to produce more equality in the whole set of social relations to which the educational system is linked. It is difficult to give a capsule example of such a complex set of relationships, but the general idea might be illustrated by Australian educational intervention in South-East Asian countries. In recent years this has come to be seen as an export industry based on fee-paying students. The 'export' of Australian education to South-East Asia in such terms reproduces over time the privileges of the urban elites in those countries, who can afford to buy professional education for their children. It promotes development, but not democratic control of development. As Duke (1986) points out, its social consequences are quite different from those of aid which works at the village level through informal adult education and institution-building. This kind of education functions to raise the villagers' capacity to articulate their own needs and pursue them over time. One is not surprised to find the elite model is more acceptable to the governments of affluent Western countries. Unjust curricula Principles of curricular justice should help in a negative way too, to identify aspects of educational practice that should be opposed. (1) The principle of participant citizenship is negated when the curriculum include practices which allow some groups to gain a greater share in social decision-making. This may be direct or indirect. Directly, formal education gives social advantages through credentialism, where educational certification is linked to closed labour markets. Curricular practices that give particular social groups superior access to credentials (e.g. academic streaming, which is known to be class- and race-linked) are to that extent unjust. Indirectly, education may give background legitimacy to the authority or power of 12 advantaged social groups. Privileged classes are legitimated where their representatives are given particular authority in curriculum decision-making e.g. elite private schools having representatives on boards and committees that determine system-wide curriculum guidelines, where disadvantaged schools have no such representatives. The privileged position of men in gender relations is legitimated (among many other ways) by physical education curricula which highlight competitive sports; given that the main competitive sports are showcases of a dominating masculinity and have the effect of 'naturalising' the superiority of men over women (Messner and Sabo 1990). (2) The principle of the interests of the least advantaged is negated by any curriculum practice which confirms or justifies their disadvantage. There have been many forms of curriculum for slavery, with the message of the 1848 hymn: The rich man in his castle, The poor man at his gate, God made them, high or lowly, And order'd their estate. Histories of education (eg Miller 1986) are full of tragi-comic quotes of this kind, consigning girls to domestic science, workers' children to training in deference and useful labour, Aboriginal children to godliness, cleanliness and semi-literacy. Nowadays no education authority in its right mind would admit to 'ordering their estate', not intentionally. But they do it all the same. When teachers in NSW public schools objected in 1990 to the 'Basic Skills Test' on the grounds that it mandates failure for the majority, and when teachers in disadvantaged schools criticised competitive testing in general because of its dire effects on children in poverty (Connell, Johnston & White 1991) they were making this point. So were teachers who have criticized streaming because of its effects on the children streamed down: Here at this school, my very first day with the children having the tests, and then next day putting them into groups, and seeing the children sitting around. And straight away they knew which was the best group, which was the worst group. And hearing a little girl say that she hadn't been picked for any group yet: 'Oh, I hope I get in this group', and 'Oh, it 13 that must be the good group because such-and-such is in it'. And then the last group called out, and she was in it. The dejected way, on the second day of the school year, that she went to that class, knowing that it was the dummy class--that was dreadful. And for all the good things that go with streaming, I would never advocate it, because of that. (Quoted in Connell 1985:17) (3) The principle of the historical production of equality is negated when socio-educational change in that direction is blocked. The recent expansion of selective schooling in NSW, a macro-streaming of the secondary curriculum, is an obvious case. The government's intention here seems to be to produce more inequality. Less obvious, but more common in educational history, is the blocking of change by the codification of culture. Curricular practices involve injustice when they reduce people's capacity to remake their world. The death of a sense of possibility may be as effective as any positive propaganda for slavery. All curricula involve codification, of course. But some rest on closed bodies of knowledge and define teaching as authoritative instruction in fixed content, others embrace cultural change and explore the creation of new meaning. Music teaching provides an interesting illustration, with its tension between a closed codification (the authoritative curriculum of the conservatories) ano an open one (usually based on rock performance). Literature is an important case where an authoritative codification- -the 'canon' of literary classics--has come under increasing criticism for excluding the voices of the less powerful (eg Brett 1984). The strategy of empowerment I have been arguing that large questions about the political meaning of education centre on the way teachers' labour is constructed and controlled; that we do not have to take a 'social reproduction' view of this matter; that we can think systematically about the potential for social justice in the organisation of curriculum. The social analysis of education can, in fact, be of practical use to teachers. The condition for this is teachers' willingness to be realistic about society: to acknowledge that educational work starts in contexts of inequality. It is essential to reject the complacency of 14 14 official statements such as the Australian Education Council's invocation of 'our democratic Australian society' (quoted above). The assumption that the society is already fully democratic, that children simply need to be trained up as participants in it, turns the idea of 'citizenship' towards a logic of regulation, ordering the formation of persons to sustain existing social relations. It obliterates the principle of education as cultural critique that is central to educational philosophy from Plato to Dewey (1916) to the present; and it invites teachers to become collaborators in the reproduction of injustice. Given an awareness of social inequality, the project of education as cultural critique implies the empowerment of the disempowered. This idea is familiar in contexts like Freire's (1972) concept of conscientization, and in the idea of a 'pedagogy of possibility' being explored now by some North American educators (eg Giroux and Simon, 1989). Here `mainstream' education discussion has something to learn from AIDS prevention education. An epidemic disease is, institutionally, medical business, so prevention education was initially designed on a medical model. Authoritative doctors, or their media simulacra, told ignorant or wilful patients (or 'risk groups') what to do. Individual 'behaviour change' was the goal sought. But from early in the 1980s gay communities developed other educational models. These centred on 'peer education' and collective community action. It was from the socially marginalized gay communities, not medical authorities, that the most effective prevention strategy, `Safe Sex', emerged (Dowsett 1990). Gay men have responded to ii.ct epidemic by attempting to increase their collective capacity to act, and specifically to act in a communal way. Change is pursued not just at the level of individual 'behaviour change', but at the level of culture and institutions. The strategy tried to make 'safe sex' normative in gay milieux, tried to change the pattern of communication about AIDS, and alter the symbolism of the disease to emphasise the capacity of 'victims' to act on their own situation. This educational effort, however, has mostly been confined to affluent milieux. There is much less mobilization among working-class men who have sex with men (Connell, Dowsett et al. 1991). Here AIDS educators need to learn from debates around schooling. The complexities of 'empowerment' are apparent in the case c7 working-class secondary schooling. Some reform proposals, including our own in Making the Difference, have urged the creation of a 'working- 15 class curriculum' more organic to working-class life than thf: academic curriculum is. This has been criticized on the grounds that it would exclude working-class kids from 'powerful knowledge' of the kind validated in the universities -natural science, economics, and the like. The criticism perhaps blurs a noticm of intellectual power with one of social recognition. Nevertheless it states an important limit in may L-ig a counter-hegemonic curriculum. One is not free simply to set up an alternative curriculum. The counter-hegemonic curriculum must incorporate and rework the core of the hegemonic curriculum. This is important, among other things, because of teachers' relationship to that curriculum. Teaching as a professional occupation has historically formed around teachers' expertise defined by the academic curriculum. To ask teachers to junk it outright would be to ask them to abandon teacher professionalism, together with the industrial strength (however limited) and the occupational identity that professionalism gives them. Rather, the approach I am suggesting would suggest a larger professionalism in which occupational knowledge and occupational ethics are expanded from the interactions of the classroom to include the consequences of those interactions. That this kind of re-thinking is a practical possibility is shown by the 'Essential Curriculum' project in Sydney (Ryan and Davey 1990). In this project, a team of teachers from disadvantaged schools have re-thought curriculum content across the board in the light of a set of agreed principles about the social purposes of schooling. Starting with existing syllabuses, recasting their content via analysis of essential common learning, the result is a specification of a teaching program which is immediately practicable in schools as they are, but also has a logic of empowerment of disadvantaged students built into it. This is only one example of a curriculum logic that has in principle very wide application. Whether it gets widely applied in practice is an open question. The mobilisation of neo- conservative ideas in education around standardized testing and the commodification of schooling is directly antagonistic to these possibilities. No one who looks at the current political scene in the OECD countries will imagine that educational progress will be easy. But the emergence in recent years of a richer and more educational understanding of the issue of educational inequality is promising. 16 Acknowledgements This paper reworks material first presented to the National Conference of the Australian Curriculum Studies Association, 1991. The ideas have developed in the course of two collaborative research projects, and I would wish to acknowledge what I have learnt from Dean Ashenden, Gary Dowsett, Sandra Kessler, Viv White and Ken Johnston. I am grateful for assistance from Marie O'Brien and Helen F-2.sson, and for a careful reading by Ian Watson which led to corrections on two important points. REFERENCES APPLE, M. (1986) Teachers and Texts: A Political Economy of Class and Gender Relations in Education (New York, Rout ledge and Kegan Paul). AUSTRALIAN EDUCATION COUNCIL (1989) Hobart Declaration on Schooling: Common and Agreed National Goals for Schooling in Australia (Hobart, AEC). BLACKBURN, J. et al. (1985) Ministerial Review of Postcompulsory Schooling (Melbourne, Dept of Education). BRETT, J. (1984) Literature and Politics. Meanjin, reprinted in J. LEE et al. (Eds) The ojgatofSieLeraaon21 (Melbourne, Meanjin/Melbourne University Press) 1990. CLARKE, E. (1987) Assessment in Queensland Secondary Schools...1964-1983 (Brisbane, Dept of Education). CLARKE, E. (1990) Assessment in Queensland Secondary Schools...1983-1990 (Brisbane, Dept of Education). CONNELL, R.W. (1985) Teachers' Work (Sydney, Allen & Unwin). CONNELL, R.W. (1988) Curriculum politics, hegemony and strategies of social change, Curriculum and Teaching, 3, pp. 63-71. CONNELL, R.W., D.J.ASHENDEN, S.KESSLER and G.W.DOWSETT (1982) Making the Difference (Sydney, Allen & Unwin). CONNELL, R.W., G.W.DOWSETT, P.RODDEN, M.D. DAVIS , L. WATSON and D. BAXTER (1991) Social class, gay men and AIDS prevention, Australian Journal of Public Health, 15, pp. 178-189. 1 7 17 CONNELL, R.W., K.M.JOHNSTON and V.M.WHITE (1991) Measuring Up: Assessment of Student Outcomes and Evaluationam Effectiveness in the Disadvantaged Schools Program and the Educational Implications in Relation to Child Poverty (Sydney, Macquarie University Centre for Applied Social Research). CONNELL, R.W., V.M.WHITE and K.M.JOHNSTON (1991) Running Twice as Hard: The Disadvantaged Schools Program (Geelong, Deakin University Press). CONNELL, W.F. (1991) Remaking Australian Education 1960-1985 (Melbourne, Australian Council for Educational Research). DEPARTMENT OF EMPLOYMENT, EDUCATION AND TRAINING (1990) A Fair Chance for All (Canberra, DEET). DEWEY, J. (1916) Democracy and Education (New York, Macmillan). DOWSETT, G.W. (1990) Reaching men who have sex with men in Australia: an overview of AIDS education, Australian Journ f iaclasLesi , 25, pp. 186-198. DUKE, C. (1986) Australian education aid -- who benefits? in: P. ELDRIDGE, D. FORBES and D. PORTER, (Eds) Australian Overseas Aid: Future Directions (Sydney, Croom Helm). FOSTER, P. (1980) Education and social inequality in sub-Saharan Africa, Journal of Modern African Studies, 18, pp. 201-236. FREIRE, P. (1972) Pedagogy of the Oppressed (Harmondsworth, Penguin). GIROUX, H.A. and SIMON, R.I. (1989) Schooling, popular culture, and a pedagogy of possibility, in: GIROUX and SIMON, (Eds) Popular Culture. Schooling and Everyday Life (Massachusetts, Bergin and Garvey). GOODSON, I. (Ed) (1985) Social Histories of Secondary Curriculum (London, Falmer). GOODSON, I. (1988) The Making of Curriculum (London, Falmer). HARDING, S. (1986) The Science Question in Feminism (Ithaca, Cornell University Press). KELLER, E.F. (1985) Reflections on Gender and Science (New Haven, Yale University Press). KUHN, T. (1970) The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Chicago, University of Chicago Press). MERCHANT, C. (1983) The Death of Nature (San Francisco, Harper and Row). 1 0 18 MESSNER, M. and D.SABO (Eels) (1990) sport. Men and the Gender Order (Champaign, Human Kinetics Books). MILLER, P. (1986) Long Division: State Schooling in South Australian Society (Adelaide, Wakefield Press). PATEMAN, C. (1988) The Sexual Contract (Stanford, Stanford University Press). RAWLS, J. (1971) A Theory of Justice (Cambridge Mass., Harvard University Press). RYAN, C. and V. DAVY (1990) The Essential Curriculum Project (Sydney, DSP Metropolitan East Region). SPENCER, H. (1859) What Knowledge is of Most Worth? in: Herbert Spencer on Education (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1932). WALZER, M. (1983) Spheres of Justice, (New York, Basic Books). WHITTY, G. (1985) Sociology and School Knowledge (London, Methuen). work_ldud4i56rrcfhemdlyomh4455i ---- doi:10.3402/egp.v2i4.2107 Deakin Research Online Deakin University’s institutional research repository DDeakin Research Online Research Online This is the published version (version of record) of: Van Hooft, Stan 2009, Gillian Brock, Global justice : a cosmopolitan account, Ethics & global politics, vol. 2, no. 4, pp. 369-382. Available from Deakin Research Online: http://hdl.handle.net/10536/DRO/DU:30022910 Reproduced with kind permission of the copyright owner. Copyright : ©2009, S. van Hooft REVIEW ESSAY Global justice: a cosmopolitan account Gillian Brock, Global justice: a cosmopolitan account (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), ISBN 978-0-19-923093-8 (Hbk), 978-0-19-923094-5 (Pbk), US$110, 366 pages with index and bibliography (also available as electronic download @ US$22). Stan van Hooft* Department of Philosophy, Faculty of Arts and Education, Deakin University, Victoria, Australia Abstract This is a review of Gillian Brock’s new book, Global justice: a cosmopolitan account (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009) which sets out the central theses of the book and then offers a critical appraisal of its central arguments. My specific concern is that Brock gives an insufficiently robust account of human rights with which to define the nature of global justice and thereby leaves cosmopolitanism too vulnerable to the normative pull of local and traditional moral conceptions that fall short of the universalism that cosmopolitans should be able to embrace. Keywords: cosmopolitanism; human rights; global justice; Rawls; humanitarian intervention; global governance; liberal nationalism; democracy; equality; immigration INTRODUCTION There is an increasing literature today on cosmopolitanism and global justice in the disciplines of philosophy and international relations. Global justice: a cosmopolitan account consolidates and extends Gillian Brock’s important contributions to this literature. While some sections are based on previously published essays, this book represents a reworking, application, and deepening of her ideas. In this review essay I offer an overview of the content of the book followed by brief critical appraisal of its central arguments. My specific concern is that Brock gives an insufficiently robust account of human rights with which to define the nature of global justice and thereby *Correspondence to: Stan van Hooft, Department of Philosophy, Faculty of Arts and Education, Deakin University, 221 Burwood Highway, Burwood, VIC 3125, Australia. Email: stanvh@deakin.edu.au Ethics & Global Politics Vol. 2, No. 4, 2009, pp. 369�382 #2009 S. van Hooft. This is an Open Access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial 3.0 Unported License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc/3.0/), permitting all non-commercial use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited. Citation: Ethics & Global Politics, Vol. 2, No. 4, 2009, pp. 369�382. DOI: 10.3402/egp.v2i4.2107 369 leaves cosmopolitanism too vulnerable to the normative pull of local and traditional moral conceptions that fall short of the universalism that cosmopolitans should be able to embrace. SUMMARY OF THE BOOK The introduction presents the core thesis of the book: that the cosmopolitan vision, which sees the moral status of each individual globally as equal, can lead to a viable conception of, and program for, global justice. Brock draws several distinctions within cosmopolitanism. One is derived from Samuel Scheffler and distinguishes ‘extreme’ from ‘moderate’ cosmopolitanism. An extreme cosmopolitan thinks there is a single universally valid theory which can justify the cosmopolitan outlook, while a moderate cosmopolitan thinks that different cultural traditions can ground cosmo- politan policies upon their own moral premises. A second distinction is that between ‘weak’ and ‘strong’ cosmopolitanism where the former pursues a minimal standard of global justice while the latter seeks stronger forms of global egalitarianism. It will transpire that Brock is both a moderate and a weak cosmopolitan in these senses. Chapter two offers a literature review centered on John Rawls’s The Law of Peoples. 1 Brock offers a brief overview of that book and rehearses the considerable debate which it has generated. She rightly points out that those familiar with debates around Rawls could skip this chapter. Yet it does serve to set up the problems that she goes on to deal with. The thesis of the next chapter is that cosmopolitans should not support a globalized version of Rawls’s difference principle as derived from his A Theory of Justice, but should rather support a ‘minimum standard principle’ in which justice consists in the provision of social goods sufficient to allow even the poorest to live a life of simple human dignity by having their basic needs met. Brock imagines a ‘normative thought experiment’ not unlike Rawls’s original position in which delegates are randomly selected to attend a global conference ‘to flesh out what we can reasonably expect of one another in a way that avoids inappropriate partiality’ (48). She argues that it is a minimum standard principle that would be agreed to in such a scenario. She supports this with empirical research which shows that people in such situations do actually prefer the principle that, ‘The most just distribution of income is that which maximizes the average income only after a certain specified minimum income is guaranteed to everyone’ (55). The problem with the difference principle and that of equality of opportunity is that it is not easy to define the social goods in respect of which fair distributions or equality should obtain without appealing to culturally specific conceptions of such social goods. The issue of the goods which should be distributed justly cannot be overcome in a world marked by moral pluralism. Accordingly, it is better to focus on what is needed to live a decent life than on the ‘maximin’ principle or on equality. Without explaining exactly how, Brock suggests that a needs approach, like Martha Nussbaum’s capabilities approach, can undergird the justification of basic human rights. Indeed, she argues S. van Hooft 370 that it is superior to, and more widely applicable than, a discourse on rights because the rights discourse is convincing only in the more liberal of the world’s cultures. Moreover, the focus on needs helps us to imagine a realistic utopia. Rather than saying that a world order is just if it honors everyone’s rights, Brock argues that a global distribution is just if it meets everyone’s basic needs, where such needs are the conditions and provisions that are necessary for meaningful human agency. Chapter four discusses global governance. Brock distinguishes this from any form of global government which would extinguish national sovereignties. Rather, the issue is one of balancing the rights of sovereignty*which are already declining as a result of globalization*with the need for global cooperation in pursuit of global goals. The unfettered pursuit of the national interest on the part of states is inimical to global justice. But, says Brock following Thomas Pogge, if global governance is an instrument to secure justice, then it is currently a very poor one. In order to improve global governance, it should be made more responsive. One way that has been suggested for doing that is to make it more democratic. Brock reports on debates between David Held and Will Kymlicka on what social conditions are necessary to democratic participation. Brock doubts whether a shared collective identity is necessary for authentic democratic deliberation. Awareness of common problems, vulnerabilities and interdependence, determination to solve common problems, and minimal shared values may be sufficient. For her part, Brock proposes a model of ‘responsive democracy’ (104) which is effective in attending to people’s interests and accountable to the people affected. On this model agency could be given to suitable experts or delegates who are responsive to their constituencies. The International Criminal Court is offered as an example. She argues that we pursue global democracy not to enhance political agency but to meet people’s needs and interests. The latter can be achieved by making institutions more responsive and by giving experts more of a say. Moreover, while future generations are not political agents they do have interests. Democracy should not be held hostage to current public opinion. It is accountability that is most important. Brock concludes that global governance must be effective and accountable, and responsive forms of democracy can fulfill these desiderata even if they are less than fully participatory. Chapter five begins a series of chapters that make concrete proposals for making the world more just. It discusses Pogge’s proposals for a global resources dividend and also his criticisms of the borrowing and selling privileges enjoyed by despotic governments, and goes on to propose a series of international taxes, including the Tobin Tax, that would discourage tax havens and dishonest accounting practices such as ‘transfer pricing’ so as to promote economic development in poorer countries. These proposals would be feasible, according to Brock, even without universal agreement or global implementation. The next chapter discusses what steps need to be taken in order to protect the ‘basic liberties’ of the world’s people. The focus is upon freedom of the press and on securing criminal justice. The press can be hampered in many ways but there are currently effective NGOs which seek to protect journalists and encourage press Global justice: a cosmopolitan account 371 freedom. For its part, the International Criminal Court is playing an important role in countering the ability of a culture of impunity to protect criminals in many countries*whether corrupt government officials, warlords or drug barons. Brock argues for the relevant liberties by once again using her normative thought experiment. In such a context, ‘reasonable people will care at least a little about enjoying some freedoms’ (152) and ‘delegates would, therefore, endorse freedom of conscience, speech, dissent, and exit’ (153). The next chapter focuses almost exclusively on military forms of humanitarian intervention, and it is therefore not surprising that it endorses the use of just war principles in order to place limits on them. The central theoretical argument for justifying humanitarian intervention is drawn, once again, from Brock’s normative thought experiment. She argues that reasonable delegates to an original convention would endorse principles that would allow for humanitarian intervention because they would welcome interventions to protect their lives and basic needs if they were in the situation of the victims of oppression. Brock also cites the International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty (ICISS) report which extends the concept of sovereignty so that it includes responsibility for the internal protection of human rights. Not only is sovereignty the right not to be interfered with, but it is also the responsibility to protect the rights of citizens internally. Accordingly, a state that fails to protect its citizens forfeits its right to non-intervention because it forfeits its sovereignty. That her hypothetical normative thought experiments might not be as unequivocal as one might hope is admitted by Brock in her chapter on immigration. She here concedes that individualist cosmopolitans in such a scenario may choose a policy of open borders from behind a veil of ignorance but that those of a more communitarian bent might endorse a more restrictive policy so as to preserve the cultural homogeneity of their societies. Rather than explore these issues more fully, however, Brock takes a consequentialist view and asks who benefits from migratory movements. She highlights the costs to developing countries when their trained people leave for more lucrative jobs in developed countries*especially in the health professions. She discusses solutions that include compensation from the developed countries to cover the costs of training such people and of restoring services that are compromised by their departure. Brock also discusses the benefits and problems that flow from the remittances that migrants send home to developing countries and which contribute substantially to those economies. The virtue of this chapter is that it shows that migration is not just a matter of justice for the individuals who migrate. It is also a matter of justice for the societies they leave behind and for future generations in those societies. Brock does not discuss problems of multiculturalism arising from migration or problems relating to refugees whose reasons for migration are not economic. Chapter nine explores the possibilities for improving the lot of the poor by reforming international trade. Deriving her thought from a multitude of technical studies, she doubts that a simple liberalization of trade would always do so and argues that ‘special and differential treatment’ would often be necessary. Fair S. van Hooft 372 international trade arrangements should allow for specific needs in order to attain the goals of global justice. Similarly, there should be reform of working conditions and wages throughout the world, and efforts to link such improvements to the conditions of trade should be encouraged. Although philosophers reading the book would not be able to assess the validity of these proposals on the basis of their expertise or on the basis of the amount of information provided in this chapter, it is valuable for them to be reminded of the need to link normative proposals to concrete institutional and programmatic reforms. There is a greater need for synergies between advocacy, philosophy, political science, and economics in order to develop workable solutions, and if Brock has extended her reach beyond her own discipline in this and preceding chapters, she should be applauded for doing so. Chapter 10 returns the book to a more philosophical level of discussion. It critiques the ‘liberal nationalist’ position of such writers as Yael Tamir and David Miller which argue that our duties toward our co-nationals are stronger and more immediate than our duties to foreigners. Brock points out that both authors are inconsistent because they allow that universal and impartial considerations provide a normative backdrop and constraint on the degree to which we may favor members of our own groups. For her part, Brock argues that it is not the case that we are permitted to attend to international obligations only after we have secured national interests. ‘Rather, what we may permissibly do for co-nationals must operate within the bounds of respecting our international duties’ (262�3). This is especially true in relation to securing global justice. According to Brock, nations should secure global justice before they attend to the welfare of their own citizens. She goes on to use her normative thought experiment to suggest that delegates in an original position would agree to seeing to the needs of co-nationals only after the basic needs and liberties of all globally were secured and fair terms of cooperation across borders were established. In a dense and complex section of the chapter, Brock goes on to refute some common objections to ‘impartialism.’ Do cosmopolitan duties devalue friends and family? Should we really save the philanthropist rather than our mother from the burning building in the classic example? Are we required to be ‘neutral’ in our actions? Brock admits that constitutive relationships are valuable and associative obligations binding but she appeals to a distinction Brian Barry makes between first and second order impartiality (267). First order impartiality requires not putting your own interests or those of your family or group members first, while second order impartiality requires adherence to just institutions. Critics of impartiality attack first order impartialism, but defenders defend second order impartialism. Brock argues that in an original position no one could object to the preference parents show to their children, but they would object to institutional arrangements that are partial to members of certain casts, ethnicities, or other identity-forming groups. Moreover, they would not endorse national or cultural allegiance is a basis for partiality because this would privilege specific conceptions of the good life. The specific conception of the good life that would be being assumed here is the communitarian/nationalist one promoted by Kymlicka, Tamir, and Miller. Brock’s point is that we should not seek Global justice: a cosmopolitan account 373 to adjudicate from a nationalist perspective between the claims of national partiality and cosmopolitan impartiality because that would be to beg the question. We must suspend nationalism by adopting her normative thought experiment. To illustrate this point, Brock says that we cannot ask whether it is fair to spend the national resources primarily on internal welfare before asking whether the national resources have been fairly obtained or justly retained. ‘Nations should only distribute resources to their own members if those resources are defensibly to be used by the nation as it pleases, but we can only decide that matter if we have first determined what global justice requires of all people and nations, and what constitutes fair ownership of resources’ (269). It is only by suspending the nationalist perspective that this broader question can be broached and the claims of global justice fairly considered. Chapter 11 begins by refuting a number of further arguments for favoring co-nationals, including those that use the ‘expanding circles’ model to suggest that our obligations become less stringent as our relations to other people become more tenuous or more distant. It then returns to the argument that we have the responsibility to see that global justice criteria are met before we are morally permitted to favor co-nationals. Brock makes this point by revisiting her earlier material about the effects of migration on the provision of health care in third-world nations, along with several other cases, such as the adequate collection of taxes internationally. We can look after the needs of co-nationals, she says, provided all the necessary safeguards and provisions are in place to ensure justice for non-nationals. Chapter 12 is a rather dense and cryptic chapter that raises a number of theoretical issues. The main thrust of it seems to be to ask about the content of global justice: in respect of what do cosmopolitans insist on equality? Brock had already argued that equality of wealth distribution or of opportunities for social position is not apposite, and she is also opposed to Rawls’s difference principle. Her position is that everyone should have equal access to those conditions and resources that are required for living a minimally decent or dignified human life. This chapter adds more. Referring to the work of Elizabeth Anderson, Brock argues that recognition and the kind of status which allows one to participate in democratic decision making are the social goods which should be available equally to all. Egalitarians should secure conditions, norms, and institutions that would accord what Anderson calls ‘democratic equality’ which would ensure freedom from oppression and domination to all. Brock says that this ties in with her notion of responsive democracy. She argues that the community in which this ideal of equality should be realized is that of the whole world rather than specific states or cultural communities because the whole world is now a globalized economic system. The distribution of wealth or social goods is not what is of central importance to cosmopolitans, but rather the equal according of the kind of social respect and recognition that becomes concrete in the ability of all individuals to participate in democratic processes. The distribution of social goods and the meeting of basic needs are merely instrumental in relation to this fundamental value. An equitable distribution of social goods is a means of ensuring equality of respect. It is not the ownership of, or access to, social goods and opportunities that is of S. van Hooft 374 fundamental value to cosmopolitans but the social recognition and democratic participation that these enable. The last chapter addresses the ‘feasibility skeptics’ who think that meaningful change for the better is not possible. Brock reminds her readers of the many suggestions that she has made or reported on in the preceding chapters which show that change is possible. CRITIQUE The book covers a wide range of important topics which range from theoretical issues to practical applications of cosmopolitan principles. However, I find the sequence of chapters a little unhelpful. That the more practical chapters occur in the middle of the book results in the needs to repeat some materials at the end when the feasibility of those proposals is discussed, while the central question of how national obligations stand to cosmopolitan duties should have been resolved earlier to as to prepare for the more concrete proposals that Brock makes. Moreover, these proposals extend the scope of the book beyond the remit of philosophy. To discuss these matters with the necessary rigor would require a degree of knowledge of economics and related social sciences that philosophers as such do not have. While I admire Brock for making such proposals, it would require social scientists and social activists operating at a number of fronts and using a wide range of expertise to decide which proposals are best and how they might be implemented. The general problem here is that of making utopian thinking more realistic and feasible and this is not a problem that philosophy, as such, is equipped to deal with. What philosophy is equipped to deal with is the justification of the principles of justice which should provide the basis for such realistic utopian thinking and for responsible action to secure global justice. While the book embraces this task, I find that it falls somewhat short on its promise. There are a number of ways in which cosmopolitans can seek to justify and operationalize the principle of the equal moral status of every individual globally that is central to their outlook and to articulate what global justice might require in the light of this principle. The first of these is to apply Rawls’s difference principle globally in the way espoused by Charles Beitz and Thomas Pogge. 2 Brock rejects this approach although she uses a scenario very similar to Rawls’s original position, applied globally, to reach her own conclusions. A second way is to argue that basic human rights apply to everyone globally and that the obligation to honor those rights is incumbent on everyone globally as well*although those obligations can be fulfilled by various institutions including both national governments and transnational organizations. Brock flirts with this second approach but does not commit herself fully to it because of her preference for the discourse of needs. Let me first say why I am concerned about Brock’s reliance on her ‘normative thought experiment.’ Although I have compared it to Rawls’s original position, it is important to see that Rawls does not apply his scenario globally. One reason for this Global justice: a cosmopolitan account 375 is that he sees a domestic society as a more or less self-enclosed system of cooperation that grounds reciprocal duties of justice which do not cross the borders of that society. But a more profound reason is that he understands his scenario as an articulation of liberal assumptions about how a reasonable participant in political institutions would think in the context of an idealized decision procedure. By suspending all knowledge of how the specific interests of participants might be realized in the society that those participants are designing, they cannot but act in an impartial manner and pursue goals which any other participant could endorse. The original position constitutes them as free and equal moral persons. In this context they constitute idealized liberal political subjects who cannot but agree on institutional arrangements that are fair. In this way, Rawls sees himself as explicating the notion of an ideal liberal political participant*a notion which he assumes his readers share*and as spelling out the principles which such a participant would be rationally committed to endorsing. It is precisely because he recognizes that his model is liberal to its very core in this way that he thinks it cannot be applied globally to societies which are not liberal. It is applicable only to well-ordered societies in which the political capacities of impartiality and a sense of justice are developed so as to constitute political participants as ideal liberal subjects. But in Brock’s use of an analogous scenario she asks us to speculate as to what principles and practices would be endorsed by randomly chosen and reasonable delegates who could come from any cultural or political background. The veil of ignorance in this context would lead delegates to think in impartial terms because they would have to consider the impact of the decision upon themselves if they were to end up in the least favored position. Accordingly, any arrangement that would be so chosen would be considered by them to be fair and just. In this version, the experiment is being used to establish what global justice demands or to test arrangements as to whether they could be accepted as just by anyone at all. And then it transpires that the arrangements endorsed in such a scenario take on a liberal, individualist, and democratic hue. Rather than assuming liberalism as a background for the original position, as Rawls does, Brock seems to use her normative thought experiment to establish it. The problem with this variation on Rawls’s idea is that it cannot be assumed that participants are ideal liberal subjects who would endorse liberal outcomes. A randomly chosen delegate might be a cardinal of the Roman church, a Hindu renouncer, a Brahmin, an Imam, or an uneducated Afghan woman who had no conception of democracy. Would such delegates agree with arrangements that were fundamentally liberal in tenor? Insofar as he holds moral views with deep conviction, could the Brahmin seriously agree that an ‘untouchable’ should receive the same respect and social recognition as Brahmins, for example? Even if he imagined himself in the position of the untouchable, would he not suppose that, as an untouchable, it would be unthinkable for him to aspire to anything except the job of cleaning away human waste? If a delegate were an Afghan woman of traditional upbringing and no education, would she not think it impossible, even for herself, to participate in democratic processes that may involve disobeying her husband? S. van Hooft 376 Brock fails to see that her normative thought experiment will not inevitably promote fundamentally liberal or cosmopolitan values. Delegates are asked to consider how they themselves would react if the arrangements they agreed to yielded an outcome not acceptable to the least favored and if they were themselves those least favored. There is no allowance made for the possibility that delegates might see themselves as spokespersons for their groups and may endorse conditions which, while they would not welcome them for themselves, they consider to be necessary to the living of the good life which their tradition teaches them to accept and to endorse for their constituents. So a male delegate may endorse a restriction on a woman’s rights because he thinks that he would or should accept it if he were a woman. At the time of writing this review there were reports in the newspaper of a young woman in Malaysia who had been condemned by judges in a Sharia court to six lashes of the cane for drinking alcohol. She is reported to have said that if this punishment were the will of Allah and if it would provide a salutary example to other Muslims, then she would be happy to accept it. This would seem to imply that if she were presented with this scenario in Brock’s normative thought experiment, she would think such a punishment was fair and appropriate. There were reports also of interviews with Afghan women living in Australia who said that they could not understand why it would be worthwhile for them to vote in the Afghan elections if they were still living in that country because, according to them, voting and politics are men’s responsibilities. 3 In this way a traditionally minded delegate may think it fair to accept illiberal restrictions on basic liberties in Brock’s normative thought experi- ment. Someone who genuinely believes that adulterers should be stoned would imagine themselves accepting such a stoning in institutions set up to create social and sexual order. They would regard it as unfair, even from the victim’s point of view, to escape from such a punishment*a punishment that will have been made to seem natural and just by years of indoctrination into the ways of the tradition. A traditional moral conception may override the self-centered quest for autonomy which liberals imagine would motivate any reasonable person at all. This point might also apply to Brock’s arguments about humanitarian intervention. Some delegates may have such strong nationalist views that they would reject intervention even if it was their own individual rights which would be protected by such a violation of sovereignty. One could well imagine contemporary Chinese nationalists thinking in this way. The problem is that when we are asked to imagine what delegates would agree to in Brock’s version of the original position, we inevitably imagine them thinking as if they were liberals such as ourselves. Because our acculturation has been broadly liberal we could not imagine ourselves agreeing to what we would see as unjust and discriminatory institutions. And so we could not imagine anyone else doing so. Although Brock does back up her rejection of Rawls’s difference principle by appealing to what was actually agreed to in a series of staged psychology experiments, by creating a hypothetical scenario in which we are asked to imagine what others would agree to without adequate empirical evidence as to what they actually do agree to, we can only fall back upon our own intuitions and hypotheses about what we would agree to. But most of us are liberals in some broad sense. It therefore becomes Global justice: a cosmopolitan account 377 inevitable that the arrangements we can imagine being agreed to in the experiment are liberal arrangements. Brock’s argument commits the fallacy of begging the question. The aim of the argument is to establish that liberal cosmopolitan principles, practices, and institutions would be fair. But it then relies on the intuitions of liberal cosmopolitans to distinguish outcomes that would be fair from those which would not be. In a world of moral pluralism there are people whose ways of thinking and scales of value are simply incomprehensible to those of us who are of a modernist and liberal persuasion. The fact is that we cannot imagine how such people would decide on issues in Brock’s normative thought experiment, and hence we cannot know what they would agree to. Perhaps it is to overcome this problem that delegates in the normative thought experiment or their decisions are described as having to be ‘reasonable.’ But this specification merely exacerbates the problem. Who is to count as reasonable from our point of view? Inevitably, we would only count as reasonable people who think broadly in the way that we do. We would not count the Brahmin or the Afghan woman as reasonable because we cannot recognize the cogency of their thinking. But this really means that to be deemed reasonable in the experiment it is necessary to think in broadly liberal terms just as we do. Once again, we have created a condition for the normative thought experiment which results in the argument begging the question. It is inevitable that reasonable people will agree to liberal principles if to count as reasonable one must already be a liberal. What this shows is that a genuinely cosmopolitan theory of justice needs to dig deeper. It cannot just be a specification of what would count as criteria for justice in the view of people who already think in modernist, individualist, and liberal terms. It is one thing to say what makes a situation or an arrangement just (for example, that it secures a minimum standard of provision necessary for living a life of simple human dignity, or that it fulfills Rawls’s maximin criteria, or that it secures equality in the distribution of some specifiable social good), but it is another to say what justice is, or what is good about justice. We can ask the classic Socratic question here: is a situation just because it would be endorsed in an original position, or would it be endorsed in an original position because it is just? The first of these options is unhelpful for reasons just explained. The second option requires us to develop an account of what makes a situation just so that it would be endorsed in an original position. It might help to explain this in negative terms. A person who suffers an injustice suffers a harm. But what is the harm that constitutes the injustice? To help us understand this question let us compare two cases. First, suppose a person loses her home because it is washed away in a tsunami which no one could have reasonably warned her of or prevented. This is a harm because she has need of a home and she now does not have one. Second, suppose a person loses her home because a powerful developer bribed a local official to remove her from it so that he could acquire the land and build a beach-side resort. In both cases the woman suffers the harm of losing the home that she needs. In both cases her needs are not met. But in the second case she also suffers an injustice. (There might be those who think she suffers S. van Hooft 378 an injustice in the first scenario, but they would require a pre-modern theory in which natural disasters are seen as violating some form of cosmic justice.) So in the second case she suffers two harms: the need for a home not being met, and the injustice. This shows that, contrary to what is implied by Brock’s view, this injustice does not consist simply in the need not being met. What sense are we to make of this injustice, then? In what does this injustice consist? Would we have explained the injustice if we were to say that, in Brock’s normative thought experiment, the woman would not have endorsed any principle, practice, or institution that would allow her home to be taken away from her in this way? No, this adds nothing. It is merely another way of saying that it was unjust. Perhaps it adds that we would agree, from our liberal vantage point, that it is unjust. But what it does not tell us is what the extra harm is that she has suffered. There is some hint of an answer in Brock’s suggestion that injustice involves a lack of social recognition and respect, but then it is not clear how this woman has had her capacity for democratic participation compromised. According to Brock, it is because democratic participation matters that social recognition and respect are important. I would suggest that the extra harm is that her right to her home has been violated. The tsunami did not violate her right to her home, even though it did result in her losing her home, but the developer’s action did violate her right to her home. There were legal arrangements by virtue of which she was entitled to her home and the action of the developer circumvented these arrangements and resulted in her loss. Introducing the notion of a right here serves to introduce another relevant notion as well: namely, that of obligation. Whenever anyone has a right, someone else has an obligation. This might be an obligation to provide some good to which the recipient is entitled or it might be an obligation to desist from some harmful action. Many such positive and negative obligations are established by laws and contracts. In the case before us, there is an obligation on the part of everyone to honor the property rights of others and this obligation is a logical counterpart of the property right in question. Our developer has not fulfilled his obligation to honor the property right of the beach-side home owner and it is for this reason that she has suffered an injustice. What this example shows is that the harm of having her need for a home frustrated that is suffered by this woman is not just a result of bad luck*as it would have been had her home been destroyed by the tsunami*but is an example of injustice. And this is because her right to her home was violated by the developer who failed to fulfill his obligation to adhere to the law. Along with the harm she suffers in losing her home, the injustice she suffers is the violation of her right to her home. Of course, this shifts the focus of the argument into the nature and basis of rights. If her normative thought experiment cannot do the work that Brock wants it to, then it had better be done by a robust theory of human rights. Brock offers no such theory but does go close to it when she speaks of human needs and capabilities. She needs to go that one step further in order to show that what we need for a life of basic human dignity we also have a right to. I myself have used Brock’s earlier work and some ideas Global justice: a cosmopolitan account 379 from Martha Nussbaum 4 to develop such an argument. 5 The argument has the following structure: 1. Describe human nature in terms of what would give dignity and worth to a human life by fulfilling that nature through the exercise of essential human capabilities. 2. Note that this description is normative for all human beings. 3. Conclude from 1 and 2 that all people should be enabled to exercise the human capabilities given in that description. 4. Assert that people need the resources to exercise those capabilities rather than just wanting them (and need them even when they do not express a want for them). 5. Conclude from 3 and 4 that social institutions and individuals should not prevent the exercise of the listed human capabilities and should provide whatever assistance or resources that are needed for such exercise. This step derives obligations from needs without specifying who carries those obligations. It is open to different cultures and societies to meet them in differing ways. 6. Note that obligations and rights are symmetrical. 7. Conclude from 5 and 6 that all human beings have a right to the freedom and the necessary resources to exercise the capabilities central to human dignity. Insofar as there is an obligation*not yet allocated to anyone in particular*to meet the needs of people so that they can exercise the capabilities described and so live a human life of minimal dignity, so all people have a right to have those needs met. It is clear, however, that Brock does not want to rely on a theory of rights. In Chapter six, for example, she uses a terminology of ‘basic liberties.’ Why does Brock not use the language of basic political and civil rights in this context? Why does she not use Nussbaum’s terminology of capabilities or her own preferred discourse of human and social needs? The concept of liberties seems vague and its relation to that of rights needs to be spelt out. Moreover, to speak of liberties is, once again, to import too much of the liberal outlook (although Brock does allow for the liberty to form non-liberal associations). Perhaps the reason that Brock has chosen not to go down the path toward a robust theory of justice based on the universal value of human rights is that it would make her an ‘extreme’ cosmopolitan. In her twelfth chapter, Brock returns to the classifications of cosmopolitanism from her introduction and says, ‘I am happy to take a pluralistic line on the sources of value [of cosmopolitanism]. And on the question of whether or not multiple fundamental principles of justice might exist, I remain open-minded to the possibility there might be such, though I have not come across particularly robust arguments for these yet’ (316). This is revealing. What it shows is that Brock does not have a theory about what makes an unjust situation unjust. Using an original scenario tells us what people would choose and so gives us criteria for what situations might be classified as just or unjust, but it does not tell us why they are unjust. For this one needs a substantive theory. A theory of human S. van Hooft 380 rights is such a theory, but Brock avoids this in favor of her discussion of needs and capabilities. An extreme cosmopolitan theory of justice based on universal human rights would also help Brock in her arguments about humanitarian intervention in Chapter seven. I reported that the argument she relies on to justify such interventions is that reasonable delegates to her normative original position would agree to such interventions if they imagined their needs not being met because of tyrannical and oppressive regimes. She also mentions the ICISS principles that, first, a state which violates the rights of its citizens forfeits its sovereignty and that, second, such violations can constitute ‘just cause’ under the criteria for just war. These ICISS principles clearly show that the concept of rights plays a crucial role in this context. But the concept of rights is superior to Brock’s appeal to needs for a further reason. Using the principles of just war as both Brock and the ICISS do runs the risk of conceiving military humanitarian interventions as acts of war. In the context of the Westphalian system of mutually aggressive states, the concept of sovereignty is logically tied to that of war in that statehood relies on the ability to defend the state’s borders. Accordingly, war is primarily seen as a violation of state sovereignty. The paradigm case of a war is an invasion. Humanitarian interventions should not be thought about in this framework. It would be much better if they were thought of as police actions directed at the violators of human rights. To do this we need to use the human rights discourse rather than the vague discourse of basic needs which Brock uses. I have argued that her normative thought experiment cannot be used to establish how justice is constituted. Accordingly, if needs not being met were to be considered by delegates in the original scenario to justify interventions, this will be because of humanitarian considerations rather than considerations of justice. It will be motivated by a desire to meet the needs of victims (or by imagining what it would be like to be such a victim) rather than the determination to punish their oppressors. What the human rights discourse gives us is the ability to justify sanctions for violations. Henry Shue has offered an argument for the legitimacy of foreign intervention based on the premise that talk of human rights is empty unless we are prepared to police their observance. 6 Accordingly, the concept of policing is tied to that of human rights. Talk of human rights obliges us to provide for the protection of those rights and for the punishment of those who violate them. This is a matter of upholding international law. If military humanitarian interventions were described as police actions they would be more readily understood as attempts to back up the global human rights regime than as invasions on the part of one state or group of states into the territory of another even if it were for humanitarian reasons such as the meeting of needs. This way of thinking would require an extreme form of cosmopolitanism that we should not shy away from. Brock has gone a long way towards elucidating a cosmopolitan foundation for the norms of global justice. However, in committing herself to being only a moderate cosmopolitan she has failed to provide a robust and universally applicable theory Global justice: a cosmopolitan account 381 of justice. The fact of global moral pluralism should not be allowed to deter cosmopolitans from developing such a theory. NOTES 1. John Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999). 2. Charles Beitz, ‘International Liberalism and Distributive Justice: A Survey of Recent Thought’, World Politics 51, no. 2 (1999): 269�96. Thomas Pogge, Realizing Rawls (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1989). See also, Brian Barry, ‘Humanity and Justice in Global Perspective’, in Nomos XXIV: Ethics, Economics and the Law, eds. J. Roland Pennock and John W. Chapman (New York: New York University Press, 1982), 219�52. 3. Carolyn Webb, ‘Of Rights and Men: for Local Afghan Women Democracy still a Concept out of Their World’. The Age (August 21, 2009), 1. 4. Martha C. Nussbaum, ‘Women and Cultural Universals’ in her Sex and Social Justice (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), 29�54, 41. Nussbaum has put forward a newer version of her list of capabilities in her, Frontiers of Justice: Disability, Nationality, Species Membership (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2006), 76�77. 5. Stan van Hooft, Cosmopolitanism: A Philosophy for Global Ethics (Chesham, UK: Acumen, 2009), 79. 6. Henry Shue, ‘Conditional Sovereignty’, Res Publica 8, no. 1 (1999): 1�7. S. van Hooft 382 work_li3nyxws4bbldkv4qq2hwceuhy ---- Eschatological Justice and the Cross: Violence and Penal Substitution Boersma, Hans ABSTRACT: Recent objections to penal substitutionary views of the atonement argue that they valorize violence. This essay argues that, to the contrary, penal substitution may be viewed as a warrant of eschatological justice that offers hope both to victims and perpetrators of violence. A rejection of all penal justice would contribute to the cycle of violence. Penal justice is a last resort for the sake of God's future eschatological justice. Christ's voluntary self-sacrifice also entails that God takes the punishment for sin upon himself, thus offering the hope of eschatological justice to all. That the cross is the church's central symbol is unlikely to be disputed. Whether this symbol is positive or negative, however, is a question that tends to generate more discussion. To many Christians, the cross is the primary symbol that brings hope for the forgiveness of sins and so for the possibility of new life: Christ's death on the cross means that one's sins have been dealt with and that God's forgiveness is forthcoming. Many have drawn such comfort from the symbol of the cross that they will find it hard to imagine that it could function in any other way. Others, however, point out that the cross has functioned in violent and oppressive ways throughout the history of the church: From Constantine's vision of the cross at the eve of the battle at the Milvian Bridge in the fourth century, to the crusades in the Middle Ages, to the conquistadors in the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries, Christians have used the cross as an excuse for the use of military power, oppression, and other forms of violence. Indeed, many are asking whether the cross is perhaps an inherently violent and oppressive symbol, responsible for abuse and violence not only in the wider military and political realms but also in personal relationships and even in the intimacy of family life. The focus for apprehension about the cross is usually the idea that Jesus Christ suffered punishment for the sake of sinners. A number of feminist scholars, in particular, are of the opinion that the notion of the cross as a form of penal justice is problematic. In her recent book, Embracing Travail, Cynthia Crysdale, for instance, insists: Redemption comes to be understood (under Anselm's influence) as the requirement of a distant, omnipotent God for the satisfaction of his honor. God's mercy gets lost in the idealization of punishment and suffering, and God is seen as sadistic and bloodthirsty. Such a God and the acceptance of our deserved punishment become necessary in order for the message of salvation to mean anything.1 Punishment on the cross, Crysdale asserts, implies a bloodthirsty God. She is not alone in this criticism of the Anselmian tradition's emphasis on penal substitution. Rita Nakashima Brock also criticizes traditional atonement models, saying, "Such doctrines of salvation reflect by analogy, I believe, images of the neglect of children or, even worse, child abuse, making it acceptable as divine behavior-cosmic child abuse, as it were."2 There appears to be a growing concern about an unholy alliance between penal substitution and violence.3 Critics object that penal substitution valorizes unjust violence at both the divine and the human level: God inflicts suffering, while humans are encouraged to accept it. If these objections can be sustained, penal substitution can hardly hold out hope of reconciliation and peace, either with God or among human beings. I am not convinced, however, that the objections are particularly persuasive. On the contrary, I will argue that we may look at divine penal substitution on the cross as an instance of eschatological justice that furthers peace and reconciliation and, as such, offers hope to both victims and perpetrators of violence.4 I readily grant that not all methods of construing a theory of penal substitution are equally hopeful. It may well be that certain ways of understanding this theory have contributed to a judgmental mindset and even to violence. For example, when theories of penal substitution separate God's justice and mercy, perhaps even valorizing the former over the latter, the picture of a "bloodthirsty" God becomes understandable. Likewise, the designation of atonement as "satisfaction," focusing solely on divine wrath, obscures the all- encompassing love of God. The counsel of Nietzsche's Zarathustra is certainly to the point: "Mistrust all in whom the impulse to punish is powerful. They are people of a low sort and stock; the hangman and the bloodhound look out of their faces. Mistrust all who talk much of their justice!"5 Finally, a penal substitution model that construes the punishment of Jesus as inflicted by the Father on an innocent third party cannot avoid charges of abusive violence and injustice. It is fair to say that popular explanations of the atonement have at times fallen prey to such unfortunate misconceptions, and the church needs to be vigilant that it does not become the cause or the occasion of abusive violence.6 When arguing that penal substitution offers hope, I am saying that this is the case only for the theory as I am outlining it in this essay. CRIME, PUNISHMENT, AND JUSTICE To begin, it may be helpful to make some general comments on the nature of punishment. First, punishment assumes an authority structure. If I punish someone, I must be in a legal position to do so; it is not enough simply for me to have the power to take away certain rights or to inflict a certain kind of injury. The same act may be called a punishment in one instance and a crime in another, depending on whether the act is performed with or without the legal authority to inflict punishment. In other words, there is a difference between crime and punishment. This distinction is significant for the topic under consideration. The gospel accounts inform us that Jesus died at the hands of Jewish and Roman authorities. This brings us into the realm of punishment rather than the realm of crime. Theologically speaking, penal substitution assumes that Jesus' crucifixion was not only a human punishment but also a divine punishment. Either way, whether considered from the historical or the theological perspective, the cross is a form of punishment enacted by an authority in a legal position to execute it. Penal substitution, therefore, takes us into the realm of punishment, not into the realm of crime. To justify violent crimes by appealing to divine penal justice thus involves a serious category mistake. Suffering as the result of crime is simply a different kind of suffering than Christ's suffering on the cross. The notions of crime and punishment are not the same, and human criminal behavior cannot properly be modeled on an understanding of the cross as penal substitution. To be sure, it is possible to imagine a person rationalizing forms of criminal violence by means of an appeal to the cross. It is also possible to imagine that people make such a link subconsciously. Nonetheless, when an individual draws wrong inferences from a penal theory of the atonement, the error lies not with the penal theory but with the person drawing the mistaken conclusion. Admittedly, the difference between crime and punishment does not legitimize just any punishment, merely because someone who is in a legal position to do so enacts it. Jacques Derrida reminds us of the important distinction between law and justice. The law never captures justice in its entirety, and justice always needs to do more than calculate mere statistical evidence. Some laws may be patently unjust, implying that some punishments may be entirely misplaced. The injustices of historical, positive laws mean that they are always subject to revision or deconstruction, whereas the notion of justice itself cannot be deconstructed. As Derrida puts it: The structure I am describing here is a structure in which law (droit) is essentially deconstructible . . . . The fact that law is deconstructible is not bad news. We may even see in this a stroke of luck for politics, for all historical progress. But the paradox that I'd like to submit for discussion is the following: it is this deconstructible structure of law (droit), or if you prefer of justice as droit, that also insures the possibility of deconstruction. Justice in itself, if such a thing exists, outside or beyond law, is not deconstructible. No more than deconstruction itself, if such a thing exists. Deconstruction is justice.7 Justice does not blindly apply the law but looks at the particular situation and so comes to a particular decision. John D. Caputo rightly comments, therefore: "Whenever a legal system has been good, whenever it has been something more than a blind and flexible tyrant, whenever laws have protected the weak against the strong and prevented the winds of injustice from sweeping across the land, then the law has been deconstructible."8 These Derridean reflections on justice help clarify questions concerning divine justice in connection with the cross. Is divine punishment on the cross a response to transgressions of a law that has little or no resemblance to eschatological justice? Is this punishment perhaps out of proportion to the transgression that it intends to penalize? Is substitution so out of joint with standards of justice that it obstructs messianic justice? In short, does the divine punishment of Christ on the cross serve or impede the coming of eschatological justice?9 The answers to these questions determine whether God condones arbitrary violence and whether the cross perpetuates human victimization. The notion of eschatological justice is also helpful because it allows us to consider questions of mercy and forgiveness in dealing with justice. If justice always means strict retribution ("an eye for an eye and a tooth for a tooth"), then little room is left for mercy and forgiveness. If, on the other hand, justice looks beyond historically constituted laws, then it is not primarily interested in an uncompromising enforcement of the law. The application of justice, in that case, will take considerations of a higher order into account. It seems obvious that strict retribution does not always encourage the overall well-being of the community. No judicial system prosecutes each and every violation of the law. Various social and economic considerations (financial costs of enforcement, the risk of crime going underground, personal extenuating circumstances, and so on) may lead to leniency in either enforcement of the law or punishment. Why, then, does God punish at all? Why does he not simply forgive? Can God not restore the divine- human relationship without resorting to something that may strike us as offensive and unworthy of God? Similar questions are often asked in connection with the North American system of criminal justice: Why punitive justice?10 Is punishment really necessary if the purpose is ultimately eschatological justice and communal peace? Does punishment not stand in the way of such an eschatological vision? In light of the variety of views on the atonement, this question certainly has its place. If any and all divine punishment would be unjust and abusive in character, then penal substitution would obviously justify the fears of violence and perpetuation of suffering. How, specifically, does punishment in connection with human relationships serve the interests of messianic justice? Punishments can serve different goals: prevention, rehabilitation, deterrence, retribution, or some combination of these four. The first three purposes of punishment in some way or other have the effect of protecting society. Even though the rehabilitative purpose is primarily focused on the cure of the criminal, it also indirectly benefits society since, if the criminal is truly cured, society will not be attacked again. The retributive purpose of punishment is aimed at something greater than society, justice itself, and thus is independent of the good (or, for that matter, the evil) that is brought to others by the execution of the punishment.11 Let us assume for a moment that we do away with all punishment. It seems to me that this would have profound consequences for both the victim and the perpetrator of the crime. It would do away not only with retribution (which aims at satisfying a perceived need for revenge, apart from considerations about the future well-being of the community), but also with the other three goals of punishment, all of which aim at eschatological justice. In terms of prevention and deterrence, an unequivocal rejection of punishment means, at the very least, that the external incentives to stop criminal behavior are being reduced. Why would people stop their criminal behavior unless they expected a legal penalty for engaging in that behavior? "Cheap grace," argues L. Gregory Jones, "denies any real need for deliverance from sin since it justifies the sin instead of the sinner. As such, cheap grace offers consolation without any change of life, without any sense of either dying or rising with Christ. Indeed, cheap grace does not require any embodiment ... ."12 Abolishing all external punishment eliminates a much-needed incentive for the perpetrator to stop the cycle of victimization and so removes the perpetrator's as well as the victim's hope of peace and justice. For the victim, a nonpenal understanding of justice carries a further consequence: There is no recourse for the offence. Regardless how little remorse an offender may show, the victim is forced to accept that society refuses to deal with the crime. The result may well be that "the world will remain forever awry, the blood of the innocent will eternally cry out to heaven."13 Even if the victim of violence is obligated to extend forgiveness, experience dictates that forgiveness is long and arduous, oftentimes not forthcoming at all. If it is to be adapted to real life, the judicial system needs to take into account the victim's difficulty in extending forgiveness to the perpetrator. The strong human propensity to harbor feelings of revenge is a reality in a sinful world: Where victimizing others is not punished, this omission may aggravate the damage done by the criminal, further diminishing prospects for reconciliation. Without punishment, it becomes more difficult to mend the tears in the social fabric and achieve justice.14 An entirely nonpenal understanding of justice is not just, simply because it does not serve eschatological justice. Interestingly, Old Testament law (without which we cannot comprehend our contemporary sense of justice) corroborates the observation that punishment may assist in reconciliation and in the flourishing of the community's justice. The Old Testament also has the peace and reconciliation of the covenant community as its ultimate concern. Judgment (mis pat) must accord with covenant faithfulness or righteousness (s^sup e^daqa).[5 Advocates of contemporary restorative justice initiatives rightly draw attention to the relational connotations of faithfulness and protection that are tied up with the concept of "righteousness."16 Hebrew law removes us far from the blindfolded Roman goddess, Justitia. Or, as Miroslav Volf puts it: "If Justitia is just, then Yahweh is patently unjust."17 Punishment in the Old Testament intends to restore severed relationships and, with this, victims' as well as perpetrators' hopes for peace and justice within the covenant community. It seems clear, therefore, that, under certain conditions, punishment can play a positive role. Rehabilitation, deterrence, and prevention may make punishment a helpful thing, Ultimately, the purpose of punishment is the community's well-being: The crime has affected the community's relationships, which need healing. Punishment can restore hope. To be sure, this apologia for punishment does not settle the question of when to punish. It dees not settle the question of the appropriate degree of punishment in particular situations. The answers to these questions will always depend on ad hoc decisions regarding particular laws and particular people in particular circumstances. MONOTHEISM, JUSTICE, AND PUNISHMENT We can now apply to justice and forgiveness some of our observations regarding the role of punishment. The positive effects of punishments apply not only within human relationships, but also within the divine- human relationship. First, the threat of divine punishment may serve as a deterrent, inclining people to live more virtuous lives, Divine punishment may mitigate the cycle of violence and victimization, thereby offering hope to perpetrator and victim alike. Second, when crime victims are aware that God punishes the criminal, it may assist them in dealing with the consequences of the crime, It may persuade them not to take revenge but to "leave room for God's wrath" (Rom 12:19), knowing that the world will not remain awry forever. Again, this knowledge of God's Justice may help the victim come to terms with the injustice that has occurred and prevent the perpetrator from being victimized in revenge, thus breaking the cycle of crime and victimization. Of course, the hypothetical justifiability of some form of divine punishment does not mean that the specific punishment of Christ on the cross necessarily was appropriate; nor does it imply that the substitutionary character of this punishment is appropriate. This leads us, then, to the particularities of the law that led to Christ's death and to the historical circumstances surrounding it. Do the particular historical structures that enabled Christ's death and their theological appropriation as penal substitution offer hope of reconciliation for both victims and perpetrators? To answer this question, we need to look at the biblical narrative within which the death of Christ occurs. What law is applied in penal substitutionary atonement? And how is this law applied in the crucifixion of Jesus Christ? The "Shema" of Deuteronomy 6:4-5 is the heart of Jewish worship: "Hear, O Israel: The LORD our God, the LORD is one. Love the LORD your God with all your heart and with all your soul and with all your strength." The particularities of Deuteronomic law all have their place in relationship to the confession of the Shema, so that transgression is to some degree a rejection of God, to whom the Israelites owe exclusive loyalty. This confession is also the ultimate standard of eschatological justice. Divine punishment thus is closely connected to the rejection of the covenant relationship between God and his people and of God as the only true God. If the Israelites consistently reject the Shema by worshipping idols, God will curse the people and inflict punishment on them: "But if your heart turns away and you are not obedient, and if you are drawn away to bow down to other gods and worship them, I declare to you this day that you will certainly be destroyed" (Deut 30:17-8). Not every transgression of the law would lead to punishment. According to Old Testament law, Israelites could atone for their sins by means of repentance and sacrifice, thereby restoring fellowship.18 The Deuteronomic law suggests, however, that Israel consistently rejected the very aim of repentance and sacrifice: restoration of, and growth in, its relationship with God. The book of Deuteronomy leads up to God's prediction of the rebellion of Israel, its rejection of the Shema, and thus to exile as the curse of the law.19 The books of Joshua through 2 Kings trace Israel's apostasy leading up to the exilic curse.20 Significantly, exile is God's last option. God resorts to this climactic punishment only when it becomes clear that Israel as a nation has consistently refused to repent and so to obtain forgiveness from God. In other words, exile as punishment for sin salvages monotheistic worship as the very heart of the law. This punishment serves justice: the worship of God, which alone constitutes complete justice. Justice, peace, and worship of the only true God are, at least in the Deuteronomic view, eschatological. Questions about the compatibility of divine forgiveness and punishment thus lead us deeper into the biblical narrative. It is certainly true that God would rather forgive than punish, often does forgive rather than punish, and that not every transgression necessitates divine punishment. But the biblical narrative highlights Israel's consistent rejection of God's plans for justice. Exile seeks to subvert this constant pattern. Israel's lack of repentance, in the end, leads to divine punishment only after Israel has consistently rejected its confession of monotheism. PENAL JUSTICE AND RECAPITULATION Punishment is eminently understandable if the very fabric of justice is at stake and if the punishment serves to advance this justice. This is exactly the role of the punishment of exile according to the biblical narrative. The Old Testament never viewed exile as the final act of abandonment. The exile served the restoration of community. Both Deuteronomy (30:1-10) and the prophets (Jer 31:31-4; Ezek 36:26-7) looked forward to a new covenant in which the relationship with God would once again be restored. Pauline theology proceeds on the assumption that not only is the exile a consequence of Israel's rejection of God, but that, at least in principle, the restoration of Israel also has occurred. Paul refers to the exilic curse of Deuteronomy as "the curse of the law" (Gal 3:13; compare Deut 27:26).21 According to some recent interpretations of Paul, Jesus recapitulated Israel's history, leading up to its exile (as the Deuteronomic curse).22 The return from this exile ultimately could be attained only by means of a resurrection from the dead, an Adamic re-creation (Ezek 37:1-14). In Christ's resurrection, Israel as a whole experiences return from exile and the human race-at least in principle-experiences its restoration and re-creation (2 Cor 5:17). This narrative implies penal substitution-but substitution of a particular kind, one more or less in line with the theology of Irenaeus (c.130-c.200 AD). In his struggle against gnosticism, Irenaeus takes the incarnation of the Word seriously. Only if the Word has truly become flesh is it possible for humans to be redeemed and taken up into the divine life: "For in what way could we be partakers of the adoption of sons," Irenaeus asks, "unless we had received from Him through the Son that fellowship which refers to Himself, unless His Word, having been made flesh, had entered into communion with us?"23 The incarnation, in Irenaeus's view, ultimately leads to the vision of God and thus to fellowship with God.24 The way Irenaeus connects incarnation and eschatological justice is intriguing. He uses the concept of recapitulation, which he understands as a retracing of the pattern of Adam's creation, life, and death that effects the restoration and renewal of humanity.25 The incarnation serves the victory of Christ over Satan and reveals to human beings what the Father is like, so that by imitating the Word, people may be restored to the image and likeness of God.26 These ideas contain the seeds of the later Christus Victor theme and of a moral influence theory of the atonement. But Irenaeus refuses to privilege these approaches at the expense of notions of sacrifice and propitiation.27 Opposing a Marcionite reading of the Old Testament, Irenaeus comments that Jesus "did not make void, but fulfilled the law, by performing the offices of the high priest, propitiating God for men, and cleansing the lepers, healing the sick, and Himself suffering death, that exiled man might go forth from condemnation, and might return without fear to his own inheritance."28 Irenaeus views Christ's sacrificial death as integral to recapitulation-a process initiated by the incarnation that leads to immortality and incorruptibility and thus to the ultimate fruition of eschatological justice.29 In a number of ways, then, the death of Christ as the penalty for human sin-whether a recapitulation of the exile of humanity from the garden of Eden or the exile of Israel from the promised land-serves the purposes of God's eschatological justice. First, the punishment that Christ bears is not simply punishment against this or that particular legal construct. Christ bears the punishment for the rejection of justice itself, of fellowship and life with the only true God. Second, Christ's punishment rehabilitates human beings to fellowship with God. In other words, God wants to give people justice even though they abandon it, so the cross means hope not only for the victim but even for the perpetrator. God does not leave people in the brokenness of injustice but allows Christ to retrace the life and death of Israel (and the life and death of Adam) for the sake of his eschatological justice. Christ's penal substitution needs to be understood in light of the goal of the punishment-restoration of justice and human fellowship with God and each other. One way of articulating the importance of this goal is by means of Richard Mouw's "important distinction between redemptive and masochistic suffering."30 We all can imagine situations in which we would give up something of ourselves in the interest of others. As a parent, I gladly do certain things for my children, even if there is a personal cost attached. I like to think that I would even be willing to die, if that were necessary to save my children's lives. We all view self-sacrifice-the giving of oneself for the sake of others-as appropriate in certain circumstances. This principle is reflected in Jesus' words, "No one has greater love than this, to lay down one's life for one's friends" (John 15:13). Though not all self-sacrifice is appropriate (and it is important not to lose sight of this fact), in certain circumstances it may be a perfectly right thing to do. Christ's sacrifice on the cross was voluntary. From the time of his temptation in the wilderness, he refused to assume the messianic kingship in a way that would subvert justice, even if that meant he could not avoid suffering. The "kingdoms of the world and their splendor," to which Satan alluded, would be his-but he would receive them only by way of suffering and death. This decision implies a significant difference between Christ's suffering and the suffering that results from abuse. Coercion on the part of the perpetrator and involuntary suffering on the part of the victim characterize abusive relationships. Neither coercion nor involuntary suffering can be attributed to Christ's atoning death on the cross. Any attempt to maintain abusive power structures by appealing to the cross is theologically incoherent and morally insidious.31 Anselm already drew attention to the voluntary character of Christ's suffering and death: "God, therefore, did not force Christ to die, there being no sin in him. Rather, he underwent death of his own accord, not out of an obedience consisting in the abandonment of his life, but out of an obedience consisting in his upholding of righteousness so bravely and pertinaciously that as a result he incurred death."32 The consistent biblical witness is that Jesus voluntarily took suffering upon himself as part of his messianic vocation to restore communal justice and peace for Israel and humanity.33 By retracing the steps of Israel and Adam, Jesus vicariously bore the suffering of abandonment and exile. The picture of an angry Father venting his fury on his child is an unbalanced caricature. It does not take into account the utter rejection of God's justice and the consistent refusal of divine forgiveness and restoration-and so it fails to acknowledge God's mercy in dealing with human rejection once and for all. It also neglects to inculcate the aim of penal substitution, namely, restoration of community and eternal peace. Finally, it ignores the voluntary character of Christ's suffering in the interest of this eschatological justice. PENAL SUBSTITUTION AND THE SUFFERING OF GOD For Irenaeus, the incarnation is an indispensable precondition for redemption and for maturation into full communion with God. Irenaeus regards the incarnation as the climax of God's progressive self-revelation, something the Bishop of Lyons traces throughout the Old Testament.34 Indeed, the biblical witness suggests that God does not remain aloof from the human condition. God enters time and space and is affected by them. The Old Testament portrays God as longing and hoping for the restoration of fellowship with Israel.35 Terence E. Fretheim draws attention to a number of passages in the Old Testament that express God's hope for the return and restoration of the people. The opening words of Isaiah 65 provide a striking example: "I was ready to be sought out by those who did not ask, to be found by those who did not seek me. I said, 'Here I am, here I am,' to a nation that did not call on my name. I held out my hands all day long to a rebellious people, who walk in a way that is not good, following their own devices . . . ."36 God yearns for a relationship with the people. This divine hope results in God's suffering emotionally for the sins of the people. In fact, God's hopes for them run so deep that, to sustain them, God bears their suffering. God even carries their burdens and sins.37 God's hope for, and commitment to, reconciliation and fellowship lead to self-giving in the incarnation, which is the climax of God's entry into the material and temporal conditions of life. In the mystery of the incarnation, God takes on human flesh and becomes subject to the conditions of human life, including violence, pain, and suffering. If the incarnation is the ultimate self-revelation of God (Heb 1:1-2), then Jesus' compassion and self- sacrifice reflect God's compassionate self-sacrifice. Irenaeus takes God's involvement with time and matter so seriously that he sees "the impassible becoming capable of suffering."38 The reality of the incarnation, with its intimate connection between the human and the divine natures, means for Irenaeus that God suffers on the cross. If the cross is indeed an instance of divine self-sacrifice, it means that in Christ God has taken the punishment onto himself and that, in the words of Karl Earth, the judge is judged in our place.39 God's self-donation in the crucifixion of Christ speaks strongly to both objections against penal substitution. First, it counters the notion that penal substitution is God's unjust infliction of suffering on an innocent third party. Since God assumes the penalty rather than punishing a third party, God can no longer be construed as a "bloodthirsty" God who punishes the innocent. Rather, by absorbing the punishment and thus enabling humankind to obtain forgiveness, God offers hope for the attainment of ultimate justice. Second, the objection that penal substitution glorifies suffering and so perpetuates victimization is also affected. Not all divine actions are to be imitated: We are not called upon to create the world or to pour out the Holy Spirit. Neither are we in a position to deal with Israel's and humanity's rejection of God's justice. It is God alone who through self-sacrifice opens the way for final justice. Not everyone may find the symbol of the cross hopeful. A careful exploration of penal substitution, however, puts to rest fears of an arbitrary and abusive God and the idea that a Christian doctrine of the atonement need perpetuate human suffering. First, since punishment and crime belong to different categories, the former may not be used to justify the latter. Second, in our sinful world, rejection of all penal justice would only contribute to the cycle of violence and therefore would not serve the hope of eschatological justice. Third, the justification of penal justice in the particular instance of the crucifixion is rooted in the divine determination to uphold the vision of eschatological justice despite the people's consistent rejection of it. Penal justice is thus a last resort that God enacts not for its own sake but for the sake of the future of his eschatological justice. In light of this unique purpose, Christ's voluntary self- donation is not a recipe for the perpetuation of human suffering but a beacon of hope for an end to all victimization. Finally, the mystery of the incarnation implies that God takes the punishment for sin upon himself, thereby offering to perpetrator and victim alike the hope of eschatological justice.40 1Cynthia S. W. Crysdale, Embracing Travail: Retrieving the Cross Today (New York: Continuum, 1999), 115. 2Rita Nakashima Brock, Journeys by Heart: A Christology of Erotic Power (New York: Crossroad, 1988), 56. 3See also Joanne Carlson Brown and Rebecca Parker, "For God So Loved the World?" in Christianity, Patriarchy and Abuse, ed. Joanne Carlson Brown and Carole R. Bonn (New York: Pilgrim, 1989), 1-30; Timothy Gorringe, God's Just Vengeance: Crime, Violence, and the Rhetoric of Salvation (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996); Aaron Milavec, "Is God Arbitrary and Sadistic? Anselm's Atonement Theory Reconsidered," Schola 4 (1981): 45-94; Craig L. Nessan, "Violence and Atonement," Dialog 35 (1996): 26-35; Darby Kathleen Ray, Deceiving the Devil: Atonement, Abuse, and Ransom (Cleveland: Pilgrim, 1998). Joel Green and Mark Baker also accept the link between violence and penal substitution in Recovering the Scandal of the Cross: Atonement in New Testament and Contemporary Contexts (Downers Grove: InterVarsity, 2000). 4In discussing penal substitution, I am aware that I am not dealing with atonement theology in its full breadth. By arguing that penal justice offers hope, I am therefore not saying that this is the only hope that the cross offers in the struggle against violence. 5Friedrich Nietzsche, "On the Tarantulas," in Thus Spoke Zarathustra (New York: Modern Library, 1995), 100. 6Compare T. Richard Snyder, The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Punishment (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 2001), 11. 7Jacques Derrida, "Force of Law: The 'Mystical Foundation of Authority,'" in Deconstruction and the Possibility of Justice, ed. Drucilla Cornell, Michel Rosenfeld, and David Gray Carlson (London: Routledge, 1992), 14-5. 8Jacques Derrida, Deconstruction in a Nutshell: A Conversation with Jacques Derrida, ed. John D. Caputo (New York: Fordham University Press, 1997), 130. 9See Nicholas Wolterstorff, "The Contours of Justice: An Ancient Call for Shalom," in God and the Victim: Theological Reflections on Evil, Victimization, Justice, and Forgiveness, ed. Lisa Barnes Lampman with Michelle D. Shattuck (Grand Rapids/Washington: Eerdmans/Neighbors Who Care, 1999), 107-30. 10Christopher D. Marshall, "The Jabs of Justice: Towards a Christian Understanding of Punishment," in Living in the LambLight: Christianity and Contemporary Challenges to the Gospel, ed. Hans Boersma (Vancouver: Regent College Publishing, 2001), 177-99. 11Donald X. Burt, Friendship and Society: An Introduction to Augustine's Practical Philosophy (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1999), 185-6. 12L. Gregory Jones, Embodying Forgiveness: A Theological Analysis (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1995), 13. 13Miroslav Volf, Exclusion and Embrace: A Theological Exploration of Identity, Otherness, and Reconciliation (Nashville: Abingdon, 1996), 294. 14Of course, one might argue that if the perpetrator repents, forgiveness rather than punishment should be forthcoming. The question is, however: whose forgiveness? A third party extending forgiveness on behalf of the victim is usually problematic, and it is hardly the judge's right to forgive a crime. 15B. Johnson points out that msspat not only refers to the verdict of the judge, but can also have the connotation of saving or punishing righteousness, so that the word is at times used in parallel to the word .fdaqa. "tSSiift mispat" in Theological Dictionary of the Old Testament, vol. 9, ed. G. Johannes Botterweok, Helmer Ringgren, and Heinz-Josef Fabry (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 1998), 93. The Pauline notion of dikaiosune tou theou likewise refers to God's covenant faithfulness, Compare N. T. Weight, What Saint Paul Really Said: Was Paul of Tarsus the Real Founder of Christianity? (Grand Rapids; Eerdmans, 1997), 93-111. 16Herrrwn Bianehi, Ethiek van het straffen (Nijkerk: Callenhach, 1964), 47-63; Daniel W. Van Ness, Crime and Its Victims (Downers Grove: InterVarsity, 1986), 113-25; Christopher D. Marshall, Beyond Retribution: A New Testament Vision for Justice, Crime, and Punishment (Grand Rapids/Auckland: Eerdmans/Lime Grove, 2001)), 35-95. 17Volf, Exclusion and Embrace, 221. 18Compare John H. Hayes, "Atonement in the Book of Leviticus," Interpretation 52 (1998): 10-2; E. P. Sanders, Paul and Palestinian Judaism: A Comparison of Patterns of Religion (Philadelphia: Fortress, 1977), 157-82. 19Deut 28:32, 36-7, 49-52, 63-68; 29:28; 31:16-22, 29. The Song of Moses that the Israelites are to sing (Deut 32) is to function as a self-indictment. 20Gordon McConville, Grace in the End: A Study in Deuteronomic Theology (Grand Rapids: Zondervan, 1993), 65-122. 21Compare Joseph P. Braswell, "The Blessing of Abraham' versus 'The Curse of the Law': Another Look at Gal 3:10-13," Westminster Theological Journal 53 (1991): 73-91; N. T. Wright, The Climax of the Covenant: Christ and the Law in Pauline Theology (Minneapolis: Fortress, 1992), 137-56. 22The notion that on the cross Jesus took Israel's exile onto himself can be argued from (1) the fact that people in Second Temple Judaism commonly looked at themselves as still being in exile, (2) the lack of fulfilment of prophetic promises of restoration, and (3) the narrative logic of Pauline theology. Compare Craig A. Evans, "Jesus and the Continuing Exile of Israel," in Jesus and the Restoration of Israel: A Critical Assessment of N. T. Wright's Jesus and the Victory of God (Downers Grove, IL/Carlisle, UK: InterVarsity/Paternoster, 1999), 77-100; N. T. Wright, The New Testament and the People of God (Minneapolis: Fortress, 1992), 268-72; N. T. Wright, Jesus and the Victory of God (Minneapolis: Fortress, 1996), 268-74. 23Irenaeus, Adversus Haereses [AH] III. 18.7, in Ante-Nicene Fathers, vol. 1, ed. Alexander Roberts and James Donaldson (Peabody: Hendrickson, 1994), 448. Compare AH III.22.1-2; V.1.2, 14.1. 24See Mary Ann Donovan, "Insights on Ministry: Irenaeus," Toronto Journal of Theology 2 (1986): 82-5. 25On Irenaeus's understanding of recapitulation, see my "Redemptive Hospitality in Irenaeus: A Model for Ecumenicity in a Violent World, Pro Ecclesia 11 (2002): 207-26; Terrence L. Tiessen, Irenaeus on the Salvation of the Unevangelized (Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow, 1993), 158-62; Gustaf Wingren, Man and the Incarnation: A Study in the Biblical Theology of Irenaeus (Edinburgh: Oliver and Boyd, 1959). 26See, e.g., AH III.18.7; V.1.1. 27Andrew J. Bandstra, "Paul and an Ancient Interpreter: A Comparison of the Teaching of Redemption in Paul and Irenaeus," Calvin Theological Journal 5 (1970): 43-63. 28Irenaeus, AH IV.8.2. 29By using the Irenaean notion of recapitulation, I am arguing that substitution docs not mean that Christ suffered instead of others, but suffered on their behalf, as their corporate representative. Compare Marshall, Beyond Retribution, 61. I argue the case for representative punishment more comprehensively in my forthcoming book, Hospitality, Violence, and the Cross: Contemporary Explorations in Atonement Theology (Grand Rapids: Baker, 2004). 30Richard J. Mouw, "Violence and the Atonement," Books & Culture (Jan./Feb. 2001), 15. 31Ray attempts to overturn this argument by saying that many battered women return to increasingly dangerous relationships and that the notion of Christ's freely chosen obedience makes self-sacrifice normative for Christians. Deceiving the Devil, 58-60. But this argument proceeds on the assumption that battered women freely choose their dangerous relationships. Freely chosen relationships naturally imply moral responsibility. Ray's argument, therefore, cannot avoid assigning blame to the victim. The wrong attribution of free choice to the victim inadvertently revictimizes her. 32Anselm, Cur Deus Homo 1.9, translated in The Major Works, ed. Brian Davies and G. R. Evans (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998). 33G. C. Berkouwer cites these passages as indicating the voluntary character of Christ's suffering: Isa 53:7, 10-2; Mark 10:45; 15:23, 36; Luke 23:46; John 10:11, 15, 17-8; 13:1. Het werk van Christus (Kampen: Kok, 1953), 154-5. 34Irenaeus, AH IV.10.1. Compare Irenaeus, Proof of the Apostolic Preaching (New York: Paulist, 1952), 25, 27, 43-85; Tiessen, Irenaeus, 142-9. 35Gerhard Sauter comments on the relation between God's hope and our hope: "There is even God's hope: We are his hope because we are expected, like the prodigal son (Luke 15:11-32). God waits patiently and tirelessly for the transfiguration of human expectations to the confidence in God's promise and creative acting. God expects us to leave room for God's redeeming activity. On this hope rests our hope." "Our Reasons for Hope," in The End of the World and the Ends of God: Science and Theology on Eschatology, ed. John Polkinghorne and Michael Welker (Harrisburg, PA: Trinity, 2000), 214. 36Fretheim also refers to the "desiderative particles" in passages of lament (Ps 81:8; Isa 48:18; Deut 5:29) and to the pain of God's dashed hopes for a relationship with God's people (Isa 42:18, 23; 48:12, 18; 50:2; 65:12; 66:4; Mic 6:3). The Suffering of God: An Old Testament Perspective (Philadelphia: Fortress, 1984), 119. 37Compare Isa 1:14; Jer 44:22. 38Irenaeus, AH III. 16.6. Compare AH III.20.4; IV.20.8. 39Karl Earth, Church Dogmatics (Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1956), IV/1, 211-83. Compare John Stott, The Cross of Christ (Downer's Grove: Intervarsity, 1986), 156-63; Miroslav Volf, "The Trinity Is Our Social Program': The Doctrine of the Trinity and the Shape of Social Engagement," Modem Theology 41 (1998): 403-23. 40I want to thank Dr. Miroslav Volf and the other members of the seminar on "Modernity, Postmodernity, and the Future of Hope" for their helpful comments on an earlier draft of this paper. The research for this paper was made possible through financial support of the Pew Charitable Trusts. I especially extend ray appreciation to Anna Mae Bush and the other staff of the Seminars in Christian Scholarship for the hospitality that they offered during my stay at Calvin College. Hans Boersma holds the Geneva Chair in Reformational Worldview Studies at Trinity Western University (Langley, BC). He is the author of several books, including A Hot Pepper Corn: Richard Baxter's Doctrine of justification in Its Seventeenth-Century Context of Controversy (1993). Copyright Theology Today Jul 2003 Provided by ProQuest Information and Learning Company. All rights Reserved work_ljr35l2hurga5fafxcgryiu3hi ---- Semenya Revised MCP Article 12/05/2011 1 Doing Epistemic (In) Justice to Semenya Abstract: In August 2009, Caster Semenya won the women’s 800m event at the International Association of Athletics Federations World Championships in Berlin. This victory became a global news story not because Semenya was a newcomer to athletics who had outperformed an established field – but because of the fact that before the race she had been asked to undergo tests to determine whether or not she was a woman. This article uses a hermeneutics of suspicion to argue that the controversy surrounding Semenya was based on a set of assumptions that, although incorrect, drew on hegemonic understandings of sex and gender that dominate the discourse of sport, and were adopted by the media without question. As a consequence, Semenya became the victim of what Miranda Fricker has termed epistemic injustice – a condition that arises when individuals or experiences are marginalized as a result of the absence of concepts and language that would enable us to articulate reality differently. Key words: Athletics, BBC, DSD, Gender Verification, Intersex, Sex Testing, Sport. Framing the Issue On 19 August 2009, 18 year-old South African Caster Semenya won the final of the women’s 800m at the International Association of Athletics Federations (IAAF) World Championships in Berlin with a time of 1:55:45. What made this victory a global news story was not that Semenya was a relative newcomer to international athletics who had finished well ahead of an established field. Rather, coverage focused on whether Semenya should have been allowed to compete at all, as it was public knowledge that before the race the IAAF had demanded that she undergo tests to determine whether or not she was a woman. Over the following months a number of stories appeared across the media, based on assumptions drawn from the framework established by the sports 12/05/2011 2 community – in particular that any evidence of maleness in a female body would confer an inherent advantage over any body that was exclusively female. This view passed without question from the sporting community (notably the athletics governing body the IAAF and other athletes) via the media into public discourse, and structured all the coverage surrounding the case – even that of pre-eminent public service broadcaster the BBC who, rather than seeking to hold the athletics authorities to account, fell into the trap of accepting the paradigm offered at the expense of delivering coverage that offered a fair and balanced analysis of the issues. The assumptions on which the BBC assumed there was consensus can be summed up as follows: (i) Semenya’s performance on 19 August was so exceptional as to raise doubts that it could have been achieved by a ‘normal’ woman. (ii) An appropriate response to concerns over exceptional female performance is to require the athlete to undergo a series of tests to determine whether or not she is ‘truly’ a woman. (iii)That if sex testing showed that her body in any way differed from that of a ‘normal’ woman, then she would have an unfair advantage over her fellow competitors. I propose to show that, although drawing on hegemonic understandings of sex and gender that are particularly prevalent in sport – a discourse based on the notion of a fundamental and deterministic binary model of sexual difference, combined with an assumption that men have an inbuilt athletic superiority - all three of these are incorrect. Responding to Foucault’s call to ‘think differently’ (1992: 9) this article seeks to address the Semenya controversy through a hermeneutics of suspicion, an approach that seeks to expose untenable claims by suspecting the credibility of the superficial text (Pepa, 2004). The original masters of suspicion (as named by Paul Ricoeur) were Marx, Nietzsche and Freud. More recently Marcella Althaus-Reid, drawing attention to the importance of 12/05/2011 3 questioning the taken-for-granted that has underpinned the most significant contributions to feminist and queer thinking, has cited Judith Butler, Mary Daly and Luce Irigary as contemporary masters (or should that be mistresses?) of suspicion (2004: 70). In what follows I will invoke my own masters of suspicion, scholars whose goal is nothing short of overturning what is perhaps one of the last remaining grand narratives – that there are two (and only two) sexes, that each of us fits neatly into one or the other, and that if the borders between the two are transgressed then something is wrong and needs to be corrected. Because the BBC (along with the media more generally) followed the lead of the IAAF in accepting the above assumptions, the controversy surrounding Caster Semenya becomes a paradigm case of what Miranda Fricker has termed epistemic injustice - an injustice caused by “structural prejudice” (2007:1). Fricker’s invocation of this term enables us to address the discourse that surrounded Semenya without implying that either the IAAF or BBC media coverage intended to harm the athlete, or were even aware that they might be doing so – even though our common-sense understandings of sex and gender make harm the inevitable result of calling into question someone’s right to membership of what is seen as a clear-cut biological category. Fricker’s work is important to my analysis, as her feminist epistemology can be linked to critiques of the science that have informed the development of our understanding of the biologically sexed body. In arguing that her task is to ask questions “in the context of socially situated accounts of our epistemic practice” (p. 3), Fricker acknowledges that the term ‘socially situated’ originates in the work of feminist philosopher of science Donna Haraway. Haraway also proposed the term material-semiotic in an attempt to reconcile, in the light of a post-Kuhnian approach to science, the problem of accounting simultaneously for the historical contingency of knowledge claims while maintaining a “no-nonsense commitment to faithful accounts of a “real” world” (Haraway, 2004: 85). The same insistence on recognising the linked nature of both the material reality of biology and the influence of culture in framing the paradigms through which we understand the real world is also central to the work of Anne Fausto-Sterling, whose Myths of Gender (1985), Sexing the Body (2000) and numerous articles have been central to drawing attention to 12/05/2011 4 inadequacies of the two-sex model of the body. This commitment to ‘reality’ is also important to Fricker, who recognizes that what she describes as “the extremist bent in so much postmodernist writing” (2007: 2) has resulted in the exclusion from Anglo- American epistemology of theorizing that politicizes epistemic practice, on the grounds that such thinking was necessarily allied with a relativistic position – regarded as anathema in the Anglo-American tradition. In the work of Fricker, epistemic injustice takes two forms – testimonial and hermeneutic. She sees the former – in which identity prejudice on the part of the hearer causes them to give the speaker less credibility – as the most common. Yet it is the second form which interests me, as hermeneutical injustice results from a “gap in collective interpretive resources” (p. 1) with the result that, because of hermeneutical impoverishment, “both speaker and hearer are labouring with the same inadequate tools” (p. 7, my emphasis). By this, Fricker means that the injustice is committed unknowingly because, collectively, we do not have the intellectual tools to unpick the assumptions inherent in the discourse. The result is a “hermeneutical darkness” (p. 149) in which some people and experiences are marginalized as a result of the absence of concepts and language that would enable us to articulate reality differently. Yet Fricker is also clear that hermeneutical injustice is not merely a case of what she calls ‘epistemic bad luck’. In the case of hermeneutical injustice it is no accident that the experience of the hermeneutically marginalised falls “down the hermeneutical cracks” – as “the whole engine of collective social meaning [is] effectively geared to keeping these obscured experiences out of sight” (p. 153), for at the heart of epistemic injustice lies a structural inequality of power. Binary Sex and the Sporting Body Sport brings the two-sex narrative into sharp relief. Reflecting on the discourses that govern the production of the sporting body, Susan Birrell and Cheryl L. Cole have noted that sport is not only a gender-producing, gender-affirming system – it is also a difference producing system. In this way it becomes one of the major sites for the naturalization of 12/05/2011 5 sex and gender differences, with the implication that superior athletic prowess is the natural domain of men (1994: 232-3). Raymond Boyle and Richard Haynes note that sport has always been a sexual battlefield, with biological difference being central to the construction of sport in society, and essentialist ideas of the body being maintained more frequently in sports discourse than in any other public domain (2000: 127-8). Deborah Stevenson agrees – suggesting that sport is a site where men can affirm physical, symbolic and economic dominance over women (2004: 280). It follows from this that hegemonic notions of masculinity and femininity are central to representations in both men’s and women’s sport, and that failure to conform to norms of physical appearance results in disciplining by the sports community, of which sports journalism is an influential pillar. The consequence is that: “Women who breach the boundaries of sports femininity and appear too muscular, powerful – or, indeed, too good – are subjected to subtle forms of discipline which ensure that they and their sport do not threaten the superiority of men” (Stevenson, 2004: 280). Corey Johnson and Beth Kivel have pointed out that the discourse of sport reflects a set of social structures that make dominant hegemonic categories seem natural, with gender grounded in an interpretation of two exclusive sexes (2007: 97), while Andrew Sharpe has gone further and argued that sport is the discourse in which the naturalization of two discrete biological sexes is most firmly entrenched (2002: 131-4). Laura Wackwitz notes that the near equation of sex with gender remains largely unquestioned in the international athletic community so that “The three terms “sex testing”, “gender verification”, and “femininity testing” are used nearly interchangeably by Olympic officials, athletes and reporters for the popular press” (2003: 554). While sport may link these terms unproblematically, the nature of their relationship has been a source of debate and tension within feminist theory since the advent of the second wave when Simone de Beauvior opened Book Two of The Second Sex (titled ‘Woman’s Life Today’), with the claim that “One is not born, but rather becomes a woman” (1983: 295). De Beauvoir’s work marked the starting point of a turn towards constructionism that sought to separate out the cultural inscription of gender from the biology of the sexed body. This move resonated with the turn to postmodernism and the privileging of 12/05/2011 6 language that (in the field of feminist theory) is frequently seen to reach its apogee with Judith Butler’s Gender Trouble (1990), which put forward a performative theory of gender, expanded on in Bodies That Matter, where Butler sought to argue that there was no sex that was not already gender, and that “the regulatory norms of “sex” work in a performative fashion to constitute the materiality of bodies” (Butler, 1993: 2). Yet what was seen as the extreme linguistic relativism of Butler’s work was contemporary with a turn to ‘corporeal feminism’ as exemplified by the work of Elizabeth Grosz (1994) and Moira Gatens (1996) that sought to reintroduce questions of the body into the heart of feminist thinking. This psychoanalytically and philosophically informed work developed alongside work by feminist biologists that sought to draw attention to the complexity of sex determination. Leading the field was Anne Fausto-Sterling whose work has, over the past twenty-five years, sought to bring to light the lack of substance behind ideas about biologically-based sex differences (see Fausto-Sterling, 1985, 1993, 2000, 2005 for key examples of her contribution to the debate). Taking a lead from Grosz’ work on the relationship of body and mind, Fausto-Sterling appropriates the analogy of the Möbius Strip to consider how biology and culture flow together in determining our understanding of the sexed body (Fausto-Sterling, 2000: 24-25). In the absence, in public discourse, of this sophisticated understanding of the relationship between sex and gender that has developed – and is continuing to develop – in gender studies, and with the imposition of femininity as the definitive marker of womanhood, the physical appearance of women sports personalities becomes key to their acceptability to fellow athletes and the sports-loving public. While what constitutes the acceptable female sporting body varies from sport to sport, there remains a core femininity that requires appropriate dress, adornment, deportment and interest in things ‘girly’ (notably clothes and shopping). Given the controversy surrounding her, it is perhaps no surprise that Semenya falls foul of this discourse. Based on her appearance alone, certain sections of the UK press had no doubt that she was not a woman. Tabloid newspaper The Sun reported her victory with the headline ‘800m and two veg’, while the ‘quality’ Daily Telegraph likened both her voice and looks to those of former World Heavyweight Boxing champion Frank Bruno (McRae, 2009). 12/05/2011 7 Even Donald McRae’s sympathetic article in Guardian Sport, published in November 2009 when the IAAF findings on Semenya were believed to be imminent, is redolent with phrases that note the way in which Semenya displays many of the signifiers of masculinity. From noting that, from a distance, even her coach cannot tell if she is a boy or a girl, McRae continues by referring to her “crunching” handshake, her muscled frame (in contrast with which Britain’s Jenny Meadows – who took Bronze in the 800m on 19 August – “looked diminutive and slight”), and her “girly lament” about not being able to go shopping any more “sounding heart-wrenching when uttered in her relatively gruff voice”. He also reports how from a young age “Caster was teased and mocked as a tomboy” and how her former headmaster reports that while she tried different hairstyles he had never seen her in a skirt or dress – “always trousers”, creating a narrative in which Semenya has always been different (McRae, 2009). The comments surrounding Semenya’s appearance, and lack of appropriate feminine behaviour, highlight the way in which sport (and sports journalism) pursues a particular narrative of what it means to be a woman, and requires participants to overcompensate in their performance of femininity in order to conform to an understanding of gender that makes athletic physicality inconsistent with womanliness. This means the more successful the athlete the more they need to dispel anxiety about their place in the hierarchy of sexual difference. If we adopt the traditional (albeit simplistic) distinction of seeing sex as biological and gender as cultural, it is clear that Semenya failed to ally suspicion about her sex through her performance of gender, with even the ANC (who were vocal in her support) acknowledging her masculine build (BBC Sport, 2009b). Yet the IAAF side-stepped the issue of her appearance (as, indeed, the controversy sought to side-step issues of race), insisting that it was her allegedly world-beating times that had prompted their concerns and led to the request that she undergo a series of tests to establish her biological sex. But were these times really so exceptional that – had they not been accompanied by comments about her appearance – warning bells would have sounded? 12/05/2011 8 An Impossible Performance for a Woman? One of the key assumptions that dominated coverage of Semenya was that her performance was so exceptional that it called into question the possibility that it had been achieved by a ‘normal’ woman. The most consistent feature of BBC Sport’s reporting of the controversy was its repeated reference to her margin of victory in the 800m final. Between 19 August and 19 November 2009 the sports section of BBC News Online ran nine articles on Semenya (BBC Sport, 2009 a,b,c,d,e,g,h,i,j) with a further article consisting of an interview with Indian athlete Santhi Soundarajan who had been banned from international athletics by the Indian Olympic Association in 2006 following a failed gender test (BBC Sport, 2009f). Five of the articles noted that Semenya had broken Zola Budd’s South African record [of 2:00:09] set in 1984, and all nine drew attention to the fact that Semenya had beaten defending IAAF world champion Janeth Jepkoskei by almost 2.5 seconds. Yet one name absent from the coverage was Pamela Jelimo, the Kenyan athlete who took the gold medal in the 800m at the 2008 Beijing Olympics. Born in December 1989 Jelimo is only 13 months older than Semenya – so she was almost exactly the same age in August 2008 as Semenya was in August 2009. And Jelimo’s athletic prowess casts Semenya’s success in a rather different light. Jelimo won her Olympic Gold with a time of 1:54:87, a time she bettered later that month (August 2008) in Zurich when she ran a time of 1:54:01 (1:44 seconds faster than Semenya ran in Berlin). Moreover – like Semenya – Jelimo came ‘out of nowhere’. Lauded by the IAAF as the 2008 Golden Girl of Athletics, the following comes from the IAAF 2008 Yearbook: In four months Jelimo went from unknown runner to Olympic gold medallist. … Jelimo began the year as a raw novice who finished 39th in the Kenyan Junior Cross Country Championship. She was not even among the 400 athletes listed in the Peter Matthews edited International Track and Field Annual for 2008. But from April to September , she proved unstoppable, winning all 15 of her races. She became Kenya’s first Olympic women’s athletics champion, took the African title, scooped $1m as the only athlete unbeaten in six Golden League meetings, and triumphed at the World Athletics Final. Yet that was only half the story. From the moment she first made her mark on the World Athletics Tour, in Hengelo in May, 12/05/2011 9 Jelimo was a record-breaking machine. She lowered the World Junior record five times and the African record four times. (http://www.iaaf.org.news/kind=103/newsid=49201.html.) The article continues by quoting Sebastian Coe (former world record holder in the men’s 800m), who praises Jelimo as a “stunning talent” with the potential to break Jarmila Kratochvilova’s 800m world record time of 1:53:28 set in 1983 (2.17 seconds faster than Semenya ran in Berlin). It seems astonishing that BBC coverage fails to make any mention of an athlete who, just one year earlier, would have left Semenya –if not trailing in the dust – at least some way behind, but who at the Berlin World Championships was eliminated during the heats. What this makes clear is that – contrary to the implications of statements made by the IAAF and subsequent media coverage - Semenya’s performance does not overshadow that of her fellow competitors. Yes, her performance at 800m in 2009 was far better than her closest rivals that year. But looked at in a broader context, and with only a marginally longer timescale, there are other women athletes whose performance is at least comparable, and even superior, but whose sex/gender has not been publicly called into question. Indeed, Semenya’s own performance record in her other event, the 1500m, provides no grounds for regarding her as mysteriously exceptional. Much was made of the vast improvement she made over 800m between 2008 and 2009, during which she knocked more than seven seconds off her personal best. Not surprisingly, similar improvement took place in her performance at 1500m. In 2008 her best time at this distance was 4:33:25 run in Rustenburg on 29 March. On 2 August 2009, at the African Junior Athletics championships in Bambous, she ran 4:08:01. Semenya did not enter the 1500m in Berlin. Yet had she done so she would have needed a significant improvement on even this performance if she were to have finished ahead of Maryam Yusuf Jamal who won the event in a time of 4:03:74. Indeed the first eight runners in the 1500m final finished with times better than Semenya’s personal best. Making reference to this would, once again, have cast Semenya’s case in a very different light by contextualising the level of her performance, yet the BBC either did not pursue this line of enquiry – or chose to ignore it in favour of a more simplistic and sensational story. 12/05/2011 10 If the most repeated aspect of BBC coverage of Semenya’s performance in Berlin was her margin of victory, the story soon developed into attempts to explain the reason for this and the nature of her supposed advantage. On 25 August, in what was described as a ‘new twist’ to the ‘saga’ BBC Sport reported that tests had revealed Semenya to have higher than normal testosterone levels (BBC Sport, 2009c,e). Later reports noted that the BBC understood that tests were likely to show Semenya had an ‘intersex’ status (BBC Sport, 2009 e,f,h), explaining this to mean that the subject has both male and female sex characteristics. How these might manifest was never specified – but as it is accepted that Semenya’s external sex characteristics are female (at birth no one questioned that she was a girl) the implication (although never stated as such) must be that her internal sex organs are male (testes) rather than female (ovaries) - leaving the reader to conclude that this, in itself, is sufficient to confer an unfair advantage on the athlete on the assumption that any evidence of maleness would inevitably confer a degree of competitive superiority over an entirely female body. Yet this is widely disputed by those who understand the range of intersex conditions and their varied effects on human physiology (Opie, 2001; Ritchie, et. al. 2008). Even if Semenya does have an increased level of testosterone, any intersex condition she might have makes it almost certain that it would provide no unfair advantage. But does she have an exceptionally high testosterone level? In its report on the ‘new twist’ to the ‘Semenya gender saga’ the BBC leads with the news that the athlete’s testosterone levels have been reported as being three times those normally expected in the female population (BBC Sport, 2009c). The report goes on to state that it was this high level of testosterone – detected by tests undertaken in South Africa – that contributed to the IAAF decision to have further tests carried out. This is subsequently linked to a “hermaphroditic or intersex condition” (BBC Sport, 2009e). But the ‘normal’ level for male testosterone is ten times the ‘normal’ female level (Connor, 2008). Context clearly matters here, as a comparison between Semenya and men would cast her test results in a very different light to a comparison with other women. But the BBC fails to provide this framing and leaves the public to draw an inappropriate inference from a fact taken out of context. 12/05/2011 11 Fausto-Sterling (2000: 170-194) provides grounds to question the significance attached to the role of hormones in sex determination, but even without taking the hermeneutics of suspicion that far, we can say that the reality is that testosterone levels vary widely not only between men and women but also within male and female populations. It is inevitable that some women will have higher than ‘normal’ levels – just as it is inevitable that, for some women, their level of testosterone will be lower than ‘normal’. Moreover, sporting competition is rife with inherent – natural - differences that confer competitive advantage on some participants. Sharpe notes that factors such as heart size, lung capacity, muscle mass and body fat often traverse, rather than parallel, the division of sex (2002: 132), and David McArdle highlights the problems involved in applying the concept of the ‘average’ person to sport, as those involved will usually possess physiques, strength and levels of stamina that are above average, almost by definition. He notes that six-foot plus biological women with considerable stamina are not exceptional, particularly in elite sport, and that in February 2007 all top 20 female tennis players in the world were at least 4cm above average height (McArdle, 2008: 48-9). Similarly, Mandy Merck (2010) has noted the range of genetic advantages (such as the height of basketball players) that sport accommodates without question. Expecting ‘normality’ in an elite athlete is a contradiction in terms. Nevertheless, in the mid-1960s a concern with ‘fairness’ resulted in the introduction of compulsory sex testing in international athletics, and the insistence in sport that it is possible to find a definitive test for womanhood . Over the years a variety of techniques were used, but as Wackwitz has noted “Each advance in screening technology has failed to provide a definitive and undisputable marker of the category “woman”” (2003: 555). Recognising that there was no definitive way to distinguish between male and female bodies, in 1992 the IAAF abandoned the notion of compulsory sex testing, with the IOC following suit after the Olympic Games in Atlanta in 1996. 12/05/2011 12 The Challenge of Determining Sex Sex testing of female athletes began during the Cold War in response to concerns that a small number of athletes from countries of the Eastern Bloc might be deliberately masquerading as women in order to gain competitive advantage and bring glory to their respective countries. The 1966 European Athletics Championships saw the introduction of ‘nude parades’ in which all female competitors were required to appear before a panel of three women doctors who confirmed they possessed female genitalia. All those attending the parade passed the visual inspection, although five East European world record holders suddenly withdrew from competition – including Russian sisters Irina and Tamara Press, who between them had dominated a variety of track and field events in the 1950 and 60s, achieving 26 world records and winning six Olympic gold medals (Ritchie et. al., 2008; Skirstad, 2000). With the possible exception of those athletes who decided not to turn up in 1966, testing has never identified an individual deliberately misrepresenting their gender, although it has created embarrassment for competitors whose bodies have, unknowingly, been found not to conform in a straightforward way to the two-sex model of sexual difference. In this context, it is important to note that the IAAF has never suggested that Semenya deliberately misrepresented herself as a woman. As the first report from the BBC made clear, IAAF spokesman Nick Davies was adamant that the situation in which the athlete found herself was not her fault, and recognised that telling someone who had been brought up female that they were, in fact, a man was a very serious issue (BBC Sport, 2009a). It is agreed by all that Semenya’s birth certificate registered her as female, that she had been brought up as a girl, and showed no evidence of external male genitalia. This raises an intriguing question. Is it possible to be brought up as a woman, but actually to be something different and not know it? The answer is yes. It is a commonplace that the first question asked about a baby is “is it a boy or a girl?”. In the vast majority of cases the answer is given immediately on the basis of an inspection of the child’s external genitalia. Only when this appears ambiguous do questions arise – at which point the situation is treated as an emergency and steps are taken to resolve the 12/05/2011 13 uncertainty (Chase, 2006; Hird, 2000). Yet as the IAAF acknowledged, sex determination is not quite that simple, as underlying non alignment of adrenal, hormonal and genetic function does not always result in the development of visually ambiguous sex (Holmes, 2009: 3). As Nick Davies indicated, sex testing is “extremely complex”. In Semenya’s case it would involve an endocrinologist, a gynaecologist, an internal medicine expert, an expert on gender and a psychologist, and the results would not be known for several weeks – or, as it turns out, months (BBC Sport 2009a). While experts in the field would agree with Davies’ assessment of the range of factors involved, many are less likely to agree that there would – eventually – be a definitive outcome. Despite this, the only expert quoted in the BBC Sport reporting, John Wass, professor of endocrinology at Oxford University, seemed not only to think that any tests would be conclusive – but that determination is simpler than the IAAF indicate. According to Wass there are three aspects that determine whether a person is a man or a woman: chromosomal sex (which can be decided in about a fortnight on the basis of a few cells scraped from inside the mouth and which show XX for a woman and XY for a man), what your external genitals look like, and, finally, what you feel you are (BBC Sport 2009b). No mention is made of the fact that these three aspects might not align. However, the medical community agrees that there are eight criteria to be taken into account in determining sex (Ljungqvist, 2000: 188), and while it is common for these to align, it is not a requirement that they do so. The many ways in which this non- alignment may manifest have tended to be known, collectively, as intersex conditions (the term adopted in BBC journalism) and became politicized in the mid 1990s through campaigning by the Intersex Society of North America (ISNA) that, encouraged by the publicity generated by an article in the New York Times by Anne Fausto-Sterling that argued for five sexes (Fausto-Sterling, 1993), sought to end early medical intervention that claimed to ‘fix’ children born with any kind of bodily anomaly on the grounds that such interventions were rarely necessary on medical grounds and tended to do more harm than good (Chase, 2006). But while the late twentieth and early twenty-first centuries 12/05/2011 14 saw the flowering of a framework for intersex that sought to confront a world informed by the premise of defect rather than of neutral variation (Holmes, 2009: 6), more recently the movement has begun to lose ground to a more medicalized outlook. While the underlying issues of biology have not changed the hermeneutics have, as suspicion is once again replaced by pathologization, with moves to have the value-neutral term intersex replaced by that of disorders of sexual development. As Alyson K. Spurgas notes: The discursive shift to DSD signifies not only the distancing of intersex from radical GLB, trans and other queer identity movements, it also heralds a new mode of association and identity around the medicalized body and a new understanding and way of living in the body itself (2009: 104). In 2006 the ISNA renamed itself the Accord Alliance and switched to the exclusive use of the nomenclature of DSD, although not all other activist organisations have followed suit. Much of the current debate draws on the fact that for many of those born with intersex conditions “this physical atypicality in no way compromises normative gender identity” (Spurgas, 2009: 97), so that they are anxious not to find themselves allied in any way with those who seek to politicize their condition and feel uncomfortable being included under the banner of queer. Framing intersex as a disorder marks a biopolitical shift that puts the focus on disciplining and normalizing bodies that fail to conform to a two-sex system. It also allows the intellectual framework within which non-binary sexual development is discussed to shift from the paradigm of queer theory to that of disability studies – perceived by many as inherently more respectable. Yet the intellectual shift from queer to disability may not prove to be the paradigm change it initially appears, as Crip Theory emerges as a discourse that seeks to politicize disability and focus on the challenges it poses for notions of bodily ability and related notions of normality (McRuer, 2006). While the debate between the paradigms of intersex and DSD continues to play out in the theoretical literature, the evidence is that the International Olympic Committee has opted to embrace the medicalized framework of DSD. In February 2010 BBC News reported 12/05/2011 15 on a meeting of the IOC General Assembly where the head of its Medical Commission, Professor Arne Ljungqvist, recommended that “strategically located centres of excellence should be established to which athletes with a DSD could be referred and, if necessary, further investigated and treated” (BBC News, 2010a). In contrast to the BBC Sport reporting, this report balanced the views of Professor Ljungqvist with recognition that the terms now being used – “eligibility, diagnosis, disorder, treatment and surgery” – had triggered alarm throughout the sporting world, particularly given that the IOC did not accompany its pronouncements on the possibility of compelling some athletes to undergo treatment with any indication of the criteria that would be used to determine gender, or even a reassurance that such treatment would only be required if it were demonstrated that any anomaly conferred an advantage. Additionally, by framing any disorder of sexual development as a defect that not only can – but should – be treated even if there is no medical reason to do so, the IOC is contributing to a discourse that pathologizes the sex-variant body and produces the very stigma that the majority of those with variant bodies are seeking to avoid, and that drives their reluctance to be part of a queer alliance. What Next for Semenya? A BBC report posted online on 10 June 2010 indicated that Caster Semenya would learn that day whether she would be able to resume her career (BBC Sport, 2010c), but a little over an hour later the page was updated to report that the news conference intended to announce the verdict had been cancelled (BBC Sport, 2010d). Both the 10 June reports reminded readers of Semenya’s margin of victory the previous August. The decision of the IAAF on Semenya’s eligibility to compete as a woman – originally scheduled for November 2009 – was announced finally at the beginning of July 2010. The announcement stated “The IAAF accepts the conclusion of a panel of medical experts that she can compete with immediate effect. Please note that the medical details of the case remain confidential” (BBC Sport, 2010e). In case anyone had forgotten the earlier coverage the report again noted Semenya’s 2.45 second margin of victory over defending champion Janeth Jepkosgei. The same day, on his BBC blog, sports correspondent Gordon Farquhar posted that, although it had never been confirmed, he was convinced that the athlete had undergone treatments “for some kind of inter-sex condition” and that 12/05/2011 16 she was now in a position to compete without unfair advantage (Farquhar, 2010). The implication here is clearly that, at the time of her August victory there had been some sort of (unspecified) advantage – despite the fact that all the medical evidence on the effects of intersex conditions on human physiology fails to support this. It is clear that, despite this outcome, the doubts raised in the Summer of 2009 remain. Semenya returned to international competition at the Lappeenranta Games in Finland a little over a week after the IAAF made their announcement. In her first 800m race for 11 months she finished in first place with a time of 2:04:22. Four days later, at another event in Finland, she won in a time of 2:02:41. In Berlin in August she broke the two minute barrier, winning in a time of 1:59:90 with her coach, Michael Seme and South African Olympic Chief Gideon Sam indicating they believed even better performances were to come. So, if Semenya has (as Farquhar feels able to state with confidence) been treated for an intersex condition or, as the IOC would seem to want it, a disorder of sexual development, her continued dominance in the event makes sense only if her condition did not play a part in her athletic performance in the first place. Despite having been cleared to run, the BBC coverage of her victory makes clear that her fellow athletes remain unconvinced that the competition is now fair, reporting misgivings from Britain’s Jemma Simpson (who finished fourth in Berlin) and Canadian Diane Cummins (who finished eighth). Demonstrating what Spurgas (2009: 108) has called ‘inter-phobia’ (which she sees as being allied to the widespread acceptance of homophobia and trans- phobia, both of which are prevalent in sport (Boyle and Haynes, 2000; Cavanagh and Sykes 2006)) Cummins is quoted as saying “Even if she is a female, she’s on the very fringe of the normal athlete female biological composition from what I understand about hormone testing. From that perspective, most of us just feel that we are literally running against a man” (BBC Sport, 2010f, my emphasis). Giving credence to these athletes’ allegations that they were facing unfair competition, the same report informs readers that Semenya had been “banned by the International Association of Athletics Federations (IAAF) after unusually high levels of testosterone were detected in a sample”, at the very least a misrepresentation of a complex situation in which Athletics South Africa chose to withdraw Semenya from international competition pending a definitive ruling from the 12/05/2011 17 IAAF, and when no official confirmation has ever been given regarding the outcome of the tests undergone by the athlete. While much of the blame for this continuing unease over Semenya must lie with the athletics governing bodies that gave credence to the rumours about her, and took almost 11 months to reach a verdict on the case, the media contributed by uncritically adopting the frame with which the sporting community presented the issue. At the time of writing Semenya has been picked for the South African team for the 2010 Commonwealth Games to be held in New Delhi in October where she is expected to win the gold medal in the 800m. Should she continue her current level of performance in the event – and particularly if she approaches or exceeds her personal best times from 2009 - it will be fascinating to see how both her fellow competitors and the sports media handle her success. (In fact she pulled out of the competition with a back injury. Media reports frequently mentioned the previous controversy.) What Next for Sex and the Body? Feminism was once content to take its lead from Simone de Beauvoir who, as I noted earlier, argued that one was not born, but rather became, a woman. But over the past two decades the commitment to distinguish between sex and gender has been supplemented by various turns in feminst theory that have sought a greater recognition of the links between the two terms, seeing them as interdependent though not interchangeable. While this may seem to bring it more in line with the discourse of the sporting establishment, which seems never to have made a distinction between sex and gender (and femininity), an important - indeed crucial - difference is the way in which a more somatic approach within feminist theory has gone hand-in-hand with an acknowledgement, based on a careful examination of the scientific evidence, that the division of individuals into two – and only two- sexes fails to recognize the complexity of the human body. The more we find out about the sexed body the less we are able to establish hard and fast differences between men and women that do not rely on cultural 12/05/2011 18 assumptions to provide their conceptual purchase. Yet rather than take the complexity of the empirical realities of the body on board, and recognize the diversity of lived human experience, the IOC seems to be turning to medicine to ‘correct’ athletic bodies so that they conform to the prevailing model of sex. If we continue to live with an insistence on a clear cut model of binary sexual difference, which may provide the comfort of certainty for the majority, the inevitable consequence will be the perpetuation of injustice towards the minority whose experience is not accorded credibility. To return to Miranda Fricker’s concept of epistemic injustice, she claims that “hermeneutical inequality is hard to detect” because the background social conditions do not give us adequate terms in which to frame the debate differently, and that “the powerful have no interest in achieving a proper interpretation” (2007: 152). What clearer illustration of this might there be than the fact that, in the case of sex and the body, rather than change the model to fit the evidence, the IOC would appear to be giving serious consideration to amending the evidence to fit the model? Writing in an issue of Hypatia that includes a Symposium on intersexuality, Sharon L. Crasnow tackles directly the issue of the relationship between models and reality when science tackles sex. In doing so she notes “What we pay attention to is determined by our interests, our models capture those interests, and the models themselves are constructed out of those concerns, but the world is not.” (Crasnow, 2001: 147, my emphasis). Like other feminist philosophers of science Crasnow is not seeking to deny the existence of objective data on the sexed body – but like Haraway with her concept of the material-semiotic, and Fausto- Sterling with the biology/culture Möbius Strip - she is drawing attention to the need to recognize that the science of the body does not exist in an intellectual and cultural vacuum. If the IOC set up centres to treat athletes diagnosed as having a ‘disorder’ of sexual development, whether or not it confers any competitive advantage, then future athletes like Caster Semenya will be required to undergo body-changing treatments, and not just (as at present) tests. The result will be that politics will have trumped science, athletics will remain under a cloud of hermeneutical darkness, and epistemic injustice will prevail. References 12/05/2011 19 Althaus-Reid, Marcella (2004) From Feminist Theology to Indecent Theology, London: SCM Press. BBC News (2010a) ‘Tension over sex testing in sport’, 15 February 2010. Available at: http://news.bbc.co.uk/go/pr/fr/-/1/hi/world/8511176.stm. Accessed 23 August 2010. BBC Sport (2009a) ‘Semenya told to take gender test’, 19 August 2009. Available at: http://news.bbc.co.uk/sport1/hi/athletics/8210471.stm. Accessed 20 August 2009. BBC Sport (2009b) ‘Semenya dismissive of gender row’, 21 August 2009. Available at: http://news.bbc.co.uk/sport1/hi/athletics/8212078.stm. Accessed 6 October 2009. BBC Sport (2009c) ‘New twist in Semenya gender saga’, 25 August 2009. Available at: http://news.bbc.co.uk/sport1/hi/athletics/8219937.stm. Accessed 6 October 2009. BBC Sport (2009d) ‘Semenya to keep World gold medal’, 10 September 2009. Available at: http://news.bbc.co.uk/sport1/hi/athletics/8245107.stm. Accessed 12 October 2009. BBC Sport (2009e) ‘SA threatens ‘war’ over Semenya’, 11 September 2009. Available at: http://news.bbc.co.uk/sport1/hi/athletics/8249948.stm. Accessed 12 October 2009. BBC Sport (2009f) Semenya ‘must not be humiliated’, 11 September 2009. Available at: http://news.bbc.co.uk/sport1/hi/athletics/8250469.stm. Accessed 6 October 2009. BBC Sport (2009g) ‘Semenya ‘let down’ in gender row’, 15 September 2009. Available at: http://news.bbc.co.uk/sport1/hi/athletics/8256522.stm. Accessed 6 October 2009. BBC Sport (2009h) ‘SA chief issues Semenya apology’, 19 September 2009. Available at: http://news.bbc.co.uk/sport1/hi/athletics/8261566.stm. Accessed 6 October 2009. BBC Sport (2009i) ‘SA chief suspended in Semenya row’, 5 November 2009. Available at: http://news.bbc.co.uk/sport1/hi/athletics/8344591.stm. Accessed 5 November 2009. BBC Sport (2009j) ‘Semenya tests not complete – IAAF’, 19 November 2009. Available at: http://news.bbc.co.uk/sport1/hi/athletics/8360295.stm. Accessed 23 November 20009. BBC Sport (2010a) ‘Doubts raised over Semenya return’ 15 January, 2010. Available at: http://news.bbc.co.uk/sport1/hi/athletics/8457819.stm. Accessed 21 January 2009. BBC Sport (2010b) ‘Caster Semenya sets sights on June return to action’ 6 April, 2010, Available at http://news.bbc.co.uk/sport1/hi/athletics/8595361.stm. Accessed 25 May 2010. 12/05/2011 20 BBC Sport (2010c) ‘Semenya set to learn test results’ 6 June 2010 09:45:22. Available at: http://news.bbc.co.uk/go/pr/fr/-/sport1/hi/athletics/8732430.stm. Accessed 6 June 2010. BBC Sport (2010d) ‘Semenya news conference cancelled’ 6 June 2010 10:50:08. Available at: http://news.bbc.co.uk/go/pr/fr/-/sport1/hi/athletics/8732430.stm. Accessed 6 June 2010. BBC Sport (2010e) ‘Athlete Semenya free to compete’ 6 July 2010. Available at: http://news.bbc.co.uk/sport1/hi/athletics/8793668.stm. Accessed 7 July 2010. BBC Sport (2010f) ‘Semenya to ignore negative jibes’ 23 August 2010. Available at: http://news.bbc.co.uk/sport1/hi/athletics/8937467.stm. Accessed 26 August 2010. Beauvoir, Simone de (1983) The Second Sex, Harmondsworth: Penguin. Birrell, Susan, and Cole, Cheryl L. (1994) ‘Double Fault: Renee Richards and the Constructions and Naturalization of Difference’ in Pamela J. Creedon (ed.) Women, Media & Sport: Challenging Gender Values, Thousand Oaks: Sage, pp 207-237. Boyle, Raymond, and Haynes, Richard (2000) Powerplay: Sport, the Media and Popular Culture, Harlow: Longman. Butler, Judith (1990) Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity, London: Routledge. Butler, Judith (1993) Bodies That Matter: On the Discursive Limits of ‘Sex’, London: Routledge. Cavanagh, Sheila L., and Sykes, Heather (2006) ‘Transsexual Bodies at the Olympics: The International Olympic Committee’s Policy on Transsexual Athletes at the 2004 Athens Summer Games’, Body & Society, Vol. 12(3): 75-102. Chase, Cheryl (2006) ‘Hermaphrodites with Attitude’ in Susan Stryker and Stephen Whittle (eds.) The Transgender Studies Reader, London: Routledge. Connor, Steve (2008) ‘Women of the Future are on Track to Run Faster Than Men’ Available at: http://www.womenssportsfoundation.org/Content/Articles/Sports-And- Fitness/W/Women-of-the-Future-Are-On-Track-to-Run-Faster-Than-Men.aspx. Accessed 12 October 2009. Crasnow, Sharon, L. (2001) ‘Models and Reality: When Science Tackles Sex’, Hypatia, Vol. 16(3): 138-148. Farquhar, Gordon (2010) ‘Semenya saga comes to just conclusion’ Available at: http://bbc.co.uk/blogs/gordonfarquar/2010/07/farquhar.html. Accessed 7 July 2010. 12/05/2011 21 Fausto-Sterling, Anne (1985) Myths of Gender, New York: Basic Books. Fausto-Sterling, Anne (1993) ‘The Five Sexes: Why Male and Female are not Enough’, The Sciences, (March/April): 20-24. [First published in the New York Times.] Fausto-Sterling, Anne (2000) Sexing the Body: Gender Politics and the Construction of Sexuality, New York: Basic Books. Fausto-Sterling, Anne (2005) ‘The Bare Bones of Sex: Part 1 – Sex and Gender’, Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society, Vol. 30(2): 1491-1527. Foucault, Michel (1992) The Use of Pleasure, Harmondsworth: Penguin. Fricker, Miranda (2007) Epistemic Injustice: Power & the Ethics of Knowing, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Gatens, Moira (1996) Imaginary Bodies: Ethics, Power and Corporeality, New York: Routledge. Grosz, Elizabeth (1994) Volatile Bodies: Towards a Corporeal Feminism, Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Haraway, Donna (2004) ‘Situated Knowledges: The Science Question in Feminism and the Privilege of Partial Perspective’ in Sandra Harding (ed.) The Feminist Standpoint Reader, London: Routledge. Hird, Myra J. (2000) ‘Gender’s nature: Intersexuality, trassexualism and the ‘sex’/’gender’ binary’, Feminist Theory, Vol. 1(3): 347-364 Holmes, Morgan M. (2009) ‘Introduction’ in Morgan Holmes (ed.) Critical Intersex, Farnham: Ashgate, pp. 1-12. Johnson, Corey W. and Kivel, Beth (2007) ‘Gender, Sexuality and Queer Theory in Sport’ in Cara Carmichael Aitchison (ed.) Sport & Gender Identities: Masculinities, Femininities and Sexualities, London: Routledge, pp93-105. IAAF (2009) ‘Pamela Jelimo is the 2008 Golden Girl of Athletics’. Available at http://www.iaaf.org.news/kind=103/newsid=49201.html. Accessed 13 January 2010. Ljungqvist, Arne (2000) ‘Gender Verification’ in Barbara L. Drinkwater (ed.) Women in Sport, Oxford: Blackwell. McArdle, David (2008) ‘Swallows and Amazons, or the Sporting Exception to the Gender Recognition Act’, Social and Legal Studies, Vol. 17(1): 39-57. 12/05/2011 22 McRae, Donald (2009) ‘Being Caster Semenya’, Guardian Sport, 14 November 2009: 1-4. McRuer, Robert (2006) Crip Theory, New York: New York University Press. Merck, Mandy (2010) ‘The Question of Caster Semenya’. Available at: http://www.radicalphilosophy.com/default.asp?channel_id=2187&editorial_id=28972. Accessed 8 March 2010. Opie, Hayden (2001) ‘Medico-Legal Issues in Sport: The View From the Grandstand’, Sydney Law Review, Vol. 23: 374-404. Pepa, Ruel F. (n.d.) ‘Nurturing the Resistance: Some important views from contemporary philosophers’, available at http://www.philosophos.com/philosophy_article_85.html. Accessed 25 January 2010. Ritchie, Robert, Reynard, John, and Lewis, Tom (2008) ‘Intersex and the Olympic Games’, Journal of the Royal Society of Medicine, Vol. 101: 395-399. Sharpe, Andrew (2002) Transgender Jurisprudence: Dysphoric Bodies of Law, London: Cavendish. Skirstad, Berit (2001) ‘Gender Verification in Competitive Sport’ in Torbjörn Tännsjö and Claudio Tamburrini (eds.) Values in Sport: Elitism, Nationalism, Gender Equality and the Scientific Manufacture of Winners, London: E & F N Spon. Spurgas, Alyson K. (2009) ‘(Un)Queering Identity: The Biosocial Production of Intersex/DSD’ in Morgan Holmes (ed.) Critical Intersex, Farnham: Ashgate, pp. 97-122. Stevenson, Deborah (2004) ‘Women, Sport and Globalisation: Competing Discourses of Sexuality and Nation’, in David Rowe (ed.) Sport, Culture and the Media: Critical Readings, Maidenhead: Open University Press, pp. 276-294. Wackwitz, Laura A. (2003) ‘Verifying the Myth: Olympic Sex Testing and the Category “Woman”, Women’s Studies International Forum, Vol. 26(6): 553-560. work_ll5t2jewubdfvp4232qjp7dgyu ---- Genetic justice must track genetic complexity. | Semantic Scholar Skip to search formSkip to main content> Semantic Scholar's Logo Search Sign InCreate Free Account You are currently offline. Some features of the site may not work correctly. DOI:10.1017/S0963180108080055 Corpus ID: 8488249Genetic justice must track genetic complexity. @article{Farrelly2008GeneticJM, title={Genetic justice must track genetic complexity.}, author={C. Farrelly}, journal={Cambridge quarterly of healthcare ethics : CQ : the international journal of healthcare ethics committees}, year={2008}, volume={17 1}, pages={ 45-53 } } C. Farrelly Published 2008 Sociology, Medicine Cambridge quarterly of healthcare ethics : CQ : the international journal of healthcare ethics committees Many different factors influence our health prospects. The food we consume, the lifestyle we live (e.g., sedentary or active), our economic prospects, our love prospects, our gender, our age, and our education all influence our expected lifetime acquisition of what John Rawls calls the "natural primary goods" (e.g., health, vigor, imagination, and intelligence). Our well-being is also influenced by the natural endowments we inherit from our parents. All people have two copies of most genes, one… Expand View on PubMed doi.org Save to Library Create Alert Cite Launch Research Feed Share This Paper 5 CitationsHighly Influential Citations 1 Background Citations 2 View All Topics from this paper Copy (object) 5 Citations Citation Type Citation Type All Types Cites Results Cites Methods Cites Background Has PDF Publication Type Author More Filters More Filters Filters Sort by Relevance Sort by Most Influenced Papers Sort by Citation Count Sort by Recency New life sciences innovation and distributive justice: rawlsian goods versus senian capabilities Theo Papaioannou Sociology Life Sciences, Society and Policy 2013 1 PDF View 1 excerpt, cites background Save Alert Research Feed Normative Theorizing about Genetics C. Farrelly Medicine Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2013 View 1 excerpt Save Alert Research Feed Market Stimulus and Genomic Justice: Evaluating the Effects of Market Access to Human Germ-Line Enhancement G. Crozier, G. K. D. C. Hajzler Economics, Medicine Kennedy Institute of Ethics journal 2010 5 Save Alert Research Feed On the Very Idea of Genetic Justice M. Loi Sociology, Medicine Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 2011 3 Highly Influenced View 6 excerpts, cites background Save Alert Research Feed Biologically Modified Justice C. Farrelly Sociology 2016 6 Save Alert Research Feed References SHOWING 1-10 OF 23 REFERENCES SORT BYRelevance Most Influenced Papers Recency FROM CHANCE TO CHOICE: GENETICS AND JUSTICE S. L. Anderson Sociology 2001 298 Save Alert Research Feed The Genetic Difference Principle C. Farrelly Sociology, Medicine The American journal of bioethics : AJOB 2004 20 PDF Save Alert Research Feed Genetic Medicine: A Logic of Disease B. Childs Medicine 1999 77 Save Alert Research Feed Genetic therapy: on the brink of a new future G. Hellermann, S. Mohapatra Medicine Genetic vaccines and therapy 2003 21 Save Alert Research Feed Enhancements and Justice: Problems in Determining the Requirements of Justice in a Genetically Transformed Society R. Lindsay Sociology, Medicine Kennedy Institute of Ethics journal 2005 28 Save Alert Research Feed Bioethics down under—medical ethics engages with political philosophy S. Holm Medicine, Sociology Journal of Medical Ethics 2005 13 PDF Save Alert Research Feed The Cost of Rights: Why Liberty Depends on Taxes S. Holmes, C. Sunstein Political Science 2000 202 PDF Save Alert Research Feed Just Constraints A. Mason British Journal of Political Science 2004 30 Save Alert Research Feed Initial sequencing and analysis of the human genome International Human Genome Sequencing Consortium Nature 2001 7,123 PDF Save Alert Research Feed Sequence the Human Genome D. Mccormick Materials Science Bio/Technology 1986 5,398 PDF Save Alert Research Feed ... 1 2 3 ... Related Papers Abstract Topics 5 Citations 23 References Related Papers Stay Connected With Semantic Scholar Sign Up About Semantic Scholar Semantic Scholar is a free, AI-powered research tool for scientific literature, based at the Allen Institute for AI. Learn More → Resources DatasetsSupp.aiAPIOpen Corpus Organization About UsResearchPublishing PartnersData Partners   FAQContact Proudly built by AI2 with the help of our Collaborators Terms of Service•Privacy Policy The Allen Institute for AI By clicking accept or continuing to use the site, you agree to the terms outlined in our Privacy Policy, Terms of Service, and Dataset License ACCEPT & CONTINUE work_llnmyfwvwzd7nmfaxzqobyqlym ---- Lasse Nielsen & David V. Axelsen Capabilitarian sufficiency: capabilities and social justice Article (Accepted version) (Refereed) Original citation: Nielsen, Lasse and Axelsen, David V. (2016) Capabilitarian sufficiency: capabilities and social justice. Journal of Human Development and Capabilities. ISSN 1945-2829 DOI: 10.1080/19452829.2016.1145632 © 2016 Human Development and Capability Association This version available at: http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/65807/ Available in LSE Research Online: March 2016 LSE has developed LSE Research Online so that users may access research output of the School. Copyright © and Moral Rights for the papers on this site are retained by the individual authors and/or other copyright owners. Users may download and/or print one copy of any article(s) in LSE Research Online to facilitate their private study or for non-commercial research. You may not engage in further distribution of the material or use it for any profit-making activities or any commercial gain. You may freely distribute the URL (http://eprints.lse.ac.uk) of the LSE Research Online website. This document is the author’s final accepted version of the journal article. There may be differences between this version and the published version. You are advised to consult the publisher’s version if you wish to cite from it. http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/cjhd20 http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/19452829.2016.1145632 https://hd-ca.org/ http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/65807/ 1 Capabilitarian Sufficiency: Capabilities and Social Justice Abstract This paper suggests an account of sufficientarianism—i.e. that justice is fulfilled when everyone has enough—laid out within a general framework of the capability approach. In doing so, it seeks to show that sufficiency is especially plausible as an ideal of social justice when constructed around key capabilitarian insights such as freedom, pluralism, and attention to empirical interconnections between central capabilities. Correspondingly, we elaborate on how a framework for evaluating social justice would look when constructed in this way and give reasons for why capabilitarians should embrace sufficientarianism. We do this by elaborating on how capabilitarian values underpin sufficiency. On this basis, we identify three categories of central capabilities; those related to biological and physical needs, those to fundamental interests of a human agent, and those to fundamental interests of a social being. In each category, we argue, achieving sufficiency requires different distributional patterns depending on how the capabilities themselves work and interrelate. This argument adds a new dimension to the way capabilitarians think about social justice and changes how we should target instances of social justice from social-political viewpoint. Keywords: The Capability Approach; Sufficiency; Social Justice; Martha Nussbaum; Pluralism; Positional Goods. Introduction The capability approach, in most instantiations, is not a theory of social justice setting out an ideal societal distribution of benefits and burdens toward which we should strive. Rather, it is a broad normative space for the evaluation of people’s well-being and freedom with many possible 2 applications (Sen 1993; 2005; Robeyns 2005). And while this ecumenical foundation and the cross-cultural applicability by which it is accompanied is one of the main strengths of the approach, it leaves open many important questions as well. Not least, it does not tell us much about which capabilities we should seek to enhance, how much we should do so, and why this is important. On the other hand, while theories of social justice often provide relatively convincing and well-developed answers to these questions, they are often developed in a philosophical space somewhat isolated from actual processes of human development. This, many would argue, limits their potential for guiding concrete agents acting in the context of such processes. In this article, we attempt to bridge the gap between these two perspectives by proposing an ideal of social justice informed by the capability approach, which we shall term capabilitarian sufficiency. In a previous article, we have suggested that a sufficientarian ideal of social justice could be a good companion for the capability approach (Axelsen & Nielsen 2015), but here we wish to specify and elaborate on how and why this is the case. Where our previous article suggested the potential for approximation between the two conceptual cores, this one actively pursues a fusion. To clarify, accounts of sufficiency entail both a positive thesis; that bringing people above some threshold is especially important, and a negative thesis; that above this threshold, inequalities are irrelevant or alternatively, a shift thesis; that inequalities above the threshold are significantly less important (see Casal 2007 and Shields 2012, respectively). The positive thesis is fairly uncontentious – both within theories of social justice and in different forms of the capability approach. The negative thesis, on the other hand, would be rejected by many who find inequalities above the threshold very relevant to justice. The acceptance of the negative thesis and the involved potential inequalities at higher levels is, thus, distinctively sufficientarian. However, accepting the negative thesis is also, we shall claim, especially well-tuned to the 3 insights of the capability approach – especially, if, as is the case here, the sufficiency threshold is built on a foundation of capabilitarian insights. Some sufficientarian theorists such as Harry Frankfurt (1987) and Robert Huseby (2010) define the threshold of sufficiency level in terms of contentment (or reasonable contentment), thus suggesting a relatively high and subjective threshold. But although contentment gives us a plausible explanation to why we should accept the negative thesis—that is, being content seems in a relevant way to weaken ones claim for additional resources—it is less successful as a reason for accepting the positive thesis. In other words, it seems fair to challenge the claim that it is critically important from a justice point of view that no one must be discontent. As Paula Casal (2007) points out, this is a general issue when employing a high threshold, since this very often means compromising universal allegiance to the reasons underlying the positive thesis. Capabilitarians have long been sceptical of relying on purely subjective evaluations when determining people’s wellbeing and relying on capabilitarian reasoning can help sufficientarians escape this danger. Other sufficientarians suggest a fairly low threshold—e.g. basic needs or basic rights (Miller 2007; Shue 1996)—but while these accounts do well in justifying what is so critically important about reaching the threshold, they face problems with explaining why inequalities above the threshold are unimportant to justice. Thus, as Casal (2007) notes their answer to the negative thesis is less plausible, as, for example, not being concerned by inequality between the super-rich and people who have barely enough seems problematic. Although, capability theorists are less explicit about inequalities at this level, we will argue that the pluralist view about what is valuable in a human life can help ground the negative thesis – and do so in a way that makes both sufficientarianism and capability theory stronger. 4 Elsewhere, we have suggested and defended a sufficientarian ideal of social justice via the concept of freedom from duress, by which we mean “the freedom from significant pressure against succeeding in central areas of life” (Axelsen & Nielsen 2015). At the heart of this account is the three-step argument that: (a) justice is concerned only with people’s opportunities in central, as opposed to non-central, areas of life; (b) that a critical threshold of sufficiency exists in each particular central area; and (c) that what effectively determines sufficiency in a specific area depends on the distributional logic of the capabilities within that area. Thus, we conclude, sufficiency as freedom from duress implies, “that justice is limited in scope, pluralist in nature, and variable in pattern” (2015). This account, we claim, does a better job than alternative sufficiency views in terms of justification of both the positive and the negative thesis. The account of sufficiency as freedom from duress is loosely informed by general insights from the capability approach, but importantly, it is not committed to it. In fact, our account is compatible with a wide range of measures that adopt an objective view of value. In this paper, we unfold a pluralist sufficientarian account of social justice explicitly within the capability approach. We do this by elaborating upon the capabilitarian notions of universally important aspects of human life and the pluralism of the human good, and their implications for sufficiency. We, then, identify three broad categories of central human capabilities that seem to be common to capability theorists: 1) capabilities related to biological and physical human needs; 2) capabilities related to fundamental interests of a human agent; and 3) capabilities related to fundamental interests of a social being, and show how these relate to sufficiency. What sufficiency means with respect to these three categories differs greatly, as they are governed by different distributional logics. These logics are understood by unpacking the dynamics in play 5 within the respective categories and how different holdings affect one’s overall level of capabilities. Elaborating on ideas which are already present in capability theory and bolstering this by way of empirical insights and the concept of positional goods, we show why inequalities above the threshold can and should matter to capability theorists and sufficientarians alike - but because these create insufficiencies. First, however, we will outline the contours of sufficiency within the normative framework of the capability approach. Sufficiency and capabilities According to capabilitarians, other theories of justice tend to overlook important aspects of human existence and differences between human lives. For example, the utilitarian focus on maximizing utility is thought to be insufficiently sensible to the societal distribution and the separateness of the individuals whose lives are at stake (Nussbaum 2006, 71-72). This point is, of course, not particular to capabilitarians, but is also held by many liberals. At the same time, theories that focus solely on the amount of resources available to a person are believed to overlook the important differences in people’s abilities to convert resources into functionings (Sen 1992), while theories focusing on welfare overestimate the reliability of subjective preferences (Nussbaum 2000, 122-142). These latter points of criticism have mainly been directed against egalitarians, but of course they apply to resource or welfare sufficientarians, like the ones mentioned above, as well. These points of criticism spell out both how capability theory lends itself best to non-welfarist accounts of social justice and the problems we avoid by formulating sufficiency in capabilitarian terms. The tenet of the capability approach is that we should be concerned with securing individual people’s capabilities—opportunity to achieve valuable combinations of functionings, 6 or, in other words, what people are actually able to do and to be (Sen 2005; Nussbaum 2006, 70)—as opposed to, say, maximizing or equalizing preference satisfaction, welfare, or wealth. Capabilitarians hold that these latter approaches simplify what is important in a human life, and that a theory of justice must necessarily be concerned with several aspects of the human reality that cannot be collapsed into one dimension without losing vital information. In Martha Nussbaum’s work, for example, the basis for this criticism lies in the notion that there is some central core to human life or, one might say, a shared base for humanity defined by central human capabilities. These different capabilities are implicitly believed to entail a threshold below which truly human functioning is not available. Getting people above this point is therefore of special importance (Nussbaum 2006, 293). In a similar vein, Amartya Sen (1999, 87) has pointed to some basic capabilities for which it is crucially important to secure functionings above a certain level. Thus, capabilitarians, at least implicitly, subscribe to an unelaborated form of the positive thesis. That is, although they are unclear about its nature and content, they agree that some level of capabilities exists, below which no one should find themselves. We will try to broaden and clarify a capabilitarian basis for accepting this claim. As mentioned, the capability approach does not usually involve taking a clear stand on social justice. This is most plainly the case with respect to the negative thesis – that is, what justice requires above the threshold. One reason for not tackling this question explicitly seems to be that their main interest lies within the current world distribution, in which far too many have far too little with regards to their central capabilities (Sen and Nussbaum, especially, are mainly concerned with the world’s developing countries). Another is that it is simply no easy task to come with a well-reflected answer. As Nussbaum points out, “it is a difficult question how far adequacy of capability requires equality of capability. Such a question can be answered only by 7 detailed thought about each capability, by asking what respect for equal human dignity requires” (Nussbaum 2011, 40-41). We will pursue a more informed basis for answering this question by elaborating on reasons for why capabilitarians should accept the negative thesis explicitly, and why they can do so without giving up their special attention to injustices in the actual world. Our account will take its point of departure in the idea that different types of capabilities are governed by different distributional logics, and thus, that what it means to have enough varies accordingly. In doing so, we will show how embracing a pluralist sufficientarian ideal of social justice can help overcome some of the shortcomings identified in the capability approach. Central capability categories As mentioned, capability theorists hold that other theories of distributive justice are not sufficiently sensitive towards important differences between human lives (i.e. their ability to convert resources into functionings), and further, that they do not distinguish adequately between different aspects of human life. This is significant, according to capabilitarians, since the most important aspects of a human life are “not commensurable in terms of any single quantative standard” (Nussbaum 2006, 166) and because some capabilities and the functionings they enable are more important than others, and should, thus, receive special attention. Capability theorists differ on, which exact capabilities are the important ones, and on how a list of such might be made. Nussbaum, most notably, has proposed an index of central human capabilities, which she claims are common to all human beings across cultures. The overall idea of Nussbaum’s work is that there is some central core to the human life defined by central human capabilities. Her list includes life; bodily health; bodily integrity; senses, imagination, and thought; emotions; practical reason; affiliation; other species; play; and control over one’s environment (2000, 78- 8 80; 2006, 6-78; 2011, 33-34). Sen, on the other hand, maintains that the capability approach ought not commit to one singular theoretical list but should be deliberately underspecified so as to ensure people’s agency, not only in regards to their effective access to the relevant functionings, but also in terms of having democratic influence on the process of deciding which capabilities are relevant. In other words, influence through choice over the process of listing relevant capabilities is in itself a freedom that should be reflected in the capabilities that people ought to have (Sen 1993; 1997; 2005; 2009, 242). Consequently, as Sen forcefully stresses, “To insist on a ‘fixed forever’ list of capabilities would deny the possibility of progress in social understanding, and also go against the productive role of public discussion, social agitation, and open debates” (Sen 2005, 160). Several other theorists have positioned themselves in relation to this distinction. In order to maintain the political impact and applicability stemming from formulations of objective lists, while at the same time safeguarding the individual agency-element that is so fundamental to the capability approach in Sen’s original form, Ingrid Robeyns has suggested to move beyond a single universal list of capabilities, and focus on coming up with relevant criteria for creating lists of capabilities for each particular use of the capability approach to a specific field (Robeyns 2011). In a similar vein, Sabina Alkire argues against Nussbaum’s account, that there can be no singular list that applies for all purposes and, thus, the selection of relevant capabilities must be done repeatedly and be sensitive to its particular use in a specific field and place (Alkire 2005; Alkire 2002, 51-53). We attempt to strike a balance between the two by not committing to a specific list of central capabilities, but instead delineating three broad categories which are distinguished not by their particular content but by their distributional logics. In other words, what sets the categories 9 apart is what it takes to achieve sufficiency with respect to this type of capability. In doing so, we seek to avoid one line of criticism made against some capability accounts suggesting that they arbitrarily exclude certain valuable capabilities (Vallentyne 2005, 361-363) without succumbing to subjective welfarism. The categories are not fixed sets or bundles of capabilities, but should be understood as a typology of capabilities with the central purpose of classifying justice-relevant capabilities in terms of how they should be distributed. Thus, the central claim here is that if we believe that there is a range of capabilities, which are all important in their own right, and that these are not commensurable, then the governing distributive principles should be informed by the particular distributional logics of the different types of capabilities. This is necessary to properly understand which level of the specific capability is required by justice – which level is sufficient. We shall proceed with the following typological categories of capabilities, which we believe any objective definition of social justice must include: 1. Capabilities related to biological and physical human needs. These are the capabilities of enjoying commodities that every human being needs in order to ensure biological and physical wellbeing. Obvious examples include the capabilities for nourishment, water, health, clean air, shelter, reproduction, sexual fulfilment, and physical security. These capabilities ensure the survival and bodily needs of members of the human species. 2. Capabilities related to fundamental interests of a human agent. These are capabilities related to individual autonomy. In other words, they are those that are needed to form and reform valuable ends. They include the capabilities of rational reflection, imagination, critical thinking, normative evaluation, functional and technical skills, understanding the implications of choices and actions for one’s life, working, having the 10 emotional capacities to feel an appropriate range of human emotions, and feeling emotional attachment with other human beings. 3. Capabilities related to fundamental interests of a social being. These are capabilities needed for pursuing one’s valuable ends within a community and, more generally, for relating to fellow human beings in the appropriate way. These include the capabilities for political freedoms such as the freedom to vote, the freedom of assembly and association, and the freedom from discrimination and oppression, but also access to some form of market in which one can trade on fair terms with others, the capability of enjoying a sufficiently high societal status, not to be dominated by others, etc. The characterization given here is not to be interpreted as the final end goal of any human life. Rather, they are three categories of capabilities that any human life must contain and thus that any plausible account of social justice needs to incorporate in a way that is sensible to the belief that the central capabilities are theoretically incommensurable — although very often in practice intertwined. This means that one cannot make simple trade-offs, and make up for a lack in one central capability by giving someone a larger amount of another (Nussbaum 2006, 167). Giving someone better capabilities for health and nourishment, for example, cannot justify curtailing their political rights, discriminating against them, or stunting their rational development. Thus, the conclusion proceeds, if justice is concerned with capabilities, it must be concerned with sufficiency in the sense of pursuing adequacy of capability; and if concerned with sufficiency in this sense, we need to understand what it takes to reach an adequate level of capability in each central area of human life. Thus, it follows that any theory, social assessment or political arrangement that adhere to justice would involve a suitable index of capabilities that revolves around a sufficiency threshold that is pluralist in nature and that this indexing procedure must 11 take into account the distributional logics of the different types of central capabilities. In order to reach a more comprehensive understanding of the content of the kind of threshold by which capabilitarians are motivated, the following sections will unfold and defend the pluralist nature of the threshold and elaborate on distributional logics of the different types of capabilities. Thresholds in plural As mentioned above, any sufficientarian theory of distributive justice must accept, and justify why we should accept, that bringing people above some critical threshold is especially important (the positive thesis). We are yet to establish, however, what is special about this threshold or, you might say, why the threshold should be given special importance. As reflected in the disagreement on which exact capabilities are most important, capabilitarians also describe the value that one obtains when getting above the threshold differently. Nussbaum has given the most explicit account of what is at stake. Leaning on Aristotle’s theory of the human good, she describes her list of central human capabilities as enabling people to live a life in human dignity (Nussbaum 2000, 70-77; 2006, 160-162; 2011, 40-41). This entails being able to function in a truly human way, as opposed to, say, an animal way. Thus, mere survival or the fulfillment of basic needs is not enough. For example, while eating just to survive might suffice for an animal, this is not enjoying food in a human way, nor, more clearly, is it a way to eat that is compatible with a life in human dignity. i For Nussbaum, then, making people sufficiently well-off means giving them adequate capabilities for a life in human dignity. Inversely, not having enough means not having these dignity-facilitating capabilities. Regardless of specific variations in foci within the capabilitarian framework, any capability-based sufficiency account implies that whether or not one is sufficiently well-off cannot be determined solely by reference to one’s own preferences or level of resources; and that 12 being sufficiently well-off does not necessarily mean being as well-off as everyone else in these areas. Taken together, we claim, these insights and intuitions stemming from within the broad framework of the capabilities approach offer a plausible foundation on which to conceptualize the content of the positive thesis. This entails bringing people above a certain capability threshold. But, whereas sufficientarians usually hold that it is especially important to bring people above a certain threshold from the point of view of justice, we claim that several such thresholds exist. Traditionally, sufficientarianism has been unfolded within the discourse of telic distributive theory and, thus, defined in relation to views of philosophers such as Larry Temkin (2003) and Derek Parfit (1997). But whereas these views all hold a one-dimensional monist view of value (such as welfarism), and, consequently, so does the sufficientarianism that defines itself in contrast with these views (such as Frankfurt 1987, Crisp 2003, and Huseby 2010), the capability approach is fundamentally pluralist. It implies that the value of the human life is inevitably multidimensional—that is, it is concerned with various types of valuable functionings and capabilities (Sen 1992, 49; Nussbaum 2000, 81) and, moreover, it acknowledges that what social justice is, in general, concerned with is, “our ability to achieve various combinations of functionings that we can compare and judge against each other in terms of what we have reasons to value” (Sen 2009, 233). Moreover, because of the capabilitarian belief in incommensurability of the central capabilities, neither will it suffice to focus on some aggregate measure of capability. Instead, we must ensure that she has an adequate level of capabilities in all the relevant spheres. While the positive thesis in Casal’s original version entails that bringing people above some critical threshold (of well-being) is especially important from the point of view of justice, we argue, that such a critical threshold exists for all central capabilities. This does not require that any account of justice must, by itself, be able to identify which specific capabilities 13 are relevant (as discussed above), but merely that, whatever these might be, the relevant threshold must be identified for every relevant capability. Taken together, we claim that the universal concern of justice in an abstract sense is to ensure that everyone has sufficient capabilities in each relevant area of human life, and that differences between those that have achieved this are irrelevant (from the point of view of justice). Again, however, it is important to note that what is required to reach the threshold and, thus, to have sufficient capabilities—that is to say, where the threshold lies—may differ among the varying capability categories. Below, we will elaborate on this difference by linking capabilitarian sufficiency with empirical insights about inequality and with the notion of positional goods in order to illuminate and outline the distributional logics of the different categories of capabilities, and make it clearer why justice should not be concerned with inequalities above the threshold—that is, why we should accept the negative thesis. Pluralism and positional goods As noted, the central capabilities must be taken as situated within distinct distributional categories, critically important in their own right, and hence a distributive scheme informed by capabilitarian sufficiency must incorporate pluralism as a fundamental component of distributive justice. This pluralism entails that the different capabilities cannot be measured on a single dimension and are also incommensurable. This may, at first glance, seem like a weakness since policy makers might be unsure about how to prioritize when unable to compare the different capabilities on a single dimension. Capability theorists, however, emphasize how this more honestly than monist theories captures the complexity of human life, and that forcing fundamentally distinct capabilities unto a single dimension often simplifies, and thereby obscures, what is actually not simple. Moreover, the entailed pluralism implies that each 14 capability should be understood appropriately based on its distributional logic. In other words, the different central capabilities constitute fundamentally different dimensions of the human good, and this distinctness is reflected in how they should be distributed. Although, this point has not been adequately elaborated within capability theory, the argumentative core is recognized within the framework. Nussbaum, for example, states that: “It appears that all the political, religious, and civil liberties can be adequately secured only if they are equally secured. To give some groups of people unequal voting rights, or unequal religious liberty, is to set them up in a position of subordination and indignity vis-à-vis others. It is to fail to recognize their equal human dignity. On the other side, there are other capabilities, closely connected with the idea of property or instrumental goods, where what seems appropriate is enough” (2006, 292-293). So, as Nussbaum indicates, sufficiency or having enough entails different distributions for different goods or capabilities. Thus, having an adequate amount of a certain capability sometimes means being above an absolute threshold that has no or little relation to what other people have, while it means having as much as or almost as much as others regarding the distribution of other capabilities. Anderson affirms the same thought; “For some functionings, equal citizenship requires equal levels. […] But for other functionings, standing as an equal does not require equal levels of functioning” (1999, 318-319). ii In other words, properly understanding the individual capabilities and how they empirically operate allows us to see how inequalities, when problematic, are actually best understood as insufficiencies. Thus, the importance of being sensitive to the particular type of capability and its distributive logic is already inherent in capability-based theories of social justice. But it is yet to be more systematically addressed and discussed how this general insight affects capabilitarian principles of social justice. In this section, we will elaborate on this idea by coupling it with the 15 notion of positional goods and empirical literature on inequality. We think that this pairing can help explain the reasoning behind Nussbaum’s and Anderson’s intuitions—and clarify our reasons for accepting the negative thesis, by showing why inequalities are sometimes important, since they can push people below the absolute threshold of sufficiency, and when this is (and is not) the case. Importantly, using the capability framework to clarify this connection comes with a set of built-in advantages. Thus, in a crucial way, constructing an account of sufficiency from within the framework of the capability approach means that one has already engaged with significant empirical insights on how different obstacles that people face may affect their opportunities to function in central areas of human life. This is because the capability approach, unlike other, less interdisciplinary frameworks for evaluating social justice, is to a large extent developed in connection with and evolves in constant interaction with empirical observations and measurements of the way in which capabilities interrelate and people’s opportunities are shaped. Which specific empirical data are necessary for a capabilitarian evaluation are, as mentioned, dependent on the nature of the task at hand. When using the framework for development studies, for example, knowledge about how capabilities are shaped and affected by cultural norms, climate, political circumstances, and geography will be important. When using the framework for evaluating social justice, on the other hand, it will be especially important to know how the levels of central capabilities – those that are important from a justice point-of-view – are determined. Especially, it will be important to know how the categories interrelate. And doing so, from within a capabilitarian framework, will entail looking at empirically informed literature that seeks to understand this link. 16 With this perspective in mind, one might look to the literature on how health is affected by people’s social standing. Michael Marmot, for example, shows on the grounds of extensive studies that people’s health; their changes of succumbing to heart diseases, cancer, strokes, and several other health related issues, are to a significant degree influenced by their opportunities for social participation and autonomy compared to their co-citizens. In other words, inequalities in societal status and autonomy affect individuals’ absolute levels of health (Marmot 2004). Or in our terms, unequal levels of capabilities related to fundamental interests of a social being brings about insufficiencies in capabilities related to biological and physical human needs. In a similar spirit, Richard Wilkinson and Kate Pickett argue that economic inequalities – and especially, through their effect on individual perceptions of their place in the social hierarchy (“how inequality gets under the skin”) – affect a broad range of societal issues such as life expectancy, violence, and mental health negatively (Wilkinson and Pickett 2010). Again, then, unequal levels of capabilities related to fundamental interests of a social being lead to people experiencing insufficiencies in other capability categories. If we care about people having enough of certain capabilities, then, there are still good reasons to worry about inequalities - but because inequalities in certain capabilities can lead to insufficiencies in others. And in other cases, because distributions are akin to zero-sum games, in which one person getting more of a certain capability necessarily means that the value of someone else’s holding decreases. In both cases, one can say that the capability has positional aspects (although, we will distinguish between the two manners in which they are positional below - as quasi-positional and positional, respectively). Positional goods are ones for which the absolute value of the good is affected by how much one has relative to others (Brighouse & Swift 2006, 472). Consequently, large inequalities 17 in the distribution of a good which is entirely positional will result in the worst-off group being below the threshold of sufficiency with respect to its value, regardless of how much they have in absolute terms. In almost all cases, individual capabilities have some positional aspects meaning that an unequal distribution will somehow affect people’s absolute level of one or more other capabilities. The presence of positional aspects, therefore, matters greatly for how specific capability thresholds should be understood. To see how this works, we now turn to the three categories of central capabilities. Generally, capabilities related to fundamental interests of a social being have strong positional aspects, meaning that one’s relative place in the distribution has a large impact on one’s absolute capabilities to succeed. This, as mentioned in the quote by Nussbaum above, is the case for voting, but it also seems to be the case for other freedoms, whose value is indirectly determined by others. Partly, this is due to the diminished capability in absolute terms of actually enjoying the freedom, but also it is because of the inherent symbolic value. Thus, for example, giving one group better capabilities for practicing their religion freely or for non-discrimination inevitably carries a message of disrespect and inferiority of status towards those left behind. It leaves them with insufficient capabilities of the relevant kind. In the same vein, it seems plausible that societal status—also in itself—be understood as a capability with strong positional aspects. This seems to be Anderson’s point when she claims that letting one group enjoy a higher level of capabilities for societal status than others necessarily leaves the lower placed individuals to “bow and scrape before others or represent themselves as inferior to others as a condition of having their claim heard” (1999, 313). In other words, the problem is that a lower status conveys a message of lesser worth in absolute terms. And this message is disrespectful, since treating one group as having less worth is failing to respond to their humanity with impartiality and failing to 18 respond properly to the equal importance of the success of each human life (Frankfurt 1997). Finally, the feeling that accompanies it is, ceteris paribus, a serious threat to one’s self-respect. Such circumstances would hinder any normal person severely in her pursuit of a flourishing life, and, thus, a relatively low status brings her below the absolute threshold. It is worth noting that this formulation avoids one line of criticism levelled against Nussbaum’s list of central capabilities; namely that it cannot explain why we should aim for an equal set of basic liberties (Richardson 2006, 450-451). Highlighting the positional aspect inherent in this type of capability, tells us why. As mentioned, most goods have some positional aspect, but capabilities related to the fundamental interests of a social being are special in this sense due to their intrinsically positional and relational qualities—they are essentially connected to people’s relations to others and their capabilities to participate in and influence collective projects. We shall therefore take the capabilities related to the fundamental interests of a social being to be positional capabilities. In these cases, what may seem like a problematic inequality above the threshold—and hence seemingly in accordance with the negative thesis—should actually be viewed as an instance of insufficiency due to the positional mechanisms involved, and thus would be condemned by the positive thesis Accordingly, for everyone to have a sufficient level of capabilities within this category of capability, the distribution must be more or less equal. Recall, however, that we are interested here only in central capabilities (regardless, as discussed, of how centrality is to be determined) and thus we should not worry about securing equality in non-central capabilities even when they have strong positional aspects. With respect to the other categories of capabilities, however, it seems more reasonable that distributional procedures ought to be designed so that everyone acquires a decent absolute 19 level of the capability in question, and that relative positions do not matter. This is generally true for capabilities that are not intrinsically positional. Neither of the two former categories of capabilities are intrinsically positional in the same sense as capabilities related to fundamental interests of a social being. Capabilities in the first category—that is, capabilities related to biological and physical human needs—such as health, housing, or nutrition are like this. It is not in itself a concern of justice that someone is more capable than others in these areas as long as everyone fares well enough. Certainly, everyone needs some level of these capabilities. But it seems wrong to say that people need equal levels of such capabilities to be able to lead dignified or reasonably successful lives. For example, one is not relevantly obstructed in a way that is problematic from the point of view of justice simply because one person has less perfectly enhanced health than others. Everyone having an equal chance of a successful life surely entails that people must have the capabilities for obtaining a decent and sufficient level of health, but it seems far too demanding to claim that everyone needs equal capabilities in order for justice to be fulfilled. That is, although deficiencies in health are critical, relative differences in individual health-functioning need not be. We shall therefore call the capabilities in this category, non- positional capabilities. Inequalities in health, for example, are often thought to be unjust and this may, one might think, serve as a counterexample to our account. However, our account of capabilitarian sufficiency can accommodate this in three ways. First, inequalities in health may affect people’s autonomy, social status, or self-respect and, thus, give rise to insufficiencies in other positional capabilities (if, for example, people of comparatively good health are met with a higher social status). Second, even if inequalities in health do not necessarily lead to insufficiencies in positional capabilities, they will often coincide with and be general symptoms of such insufficiencies since social disadvantages tend to cluster (Wolff and de-Shalit 2007, 122- 20 123; Marmot 2004, 14-15). This grounds the importance of health functioning measures such as life-expectancy in the Human Development Index and how it may play a significant role as a valid proxy for identifying the worse-off. Perceived in this way, health inequalities are worrisome—although not necessarily incidences of insufficiencies in themselves—because they highlight some societal groups that are clearly insufficiently well-off. This is aptly illustrated by Marmot’s famous account a subway ride from central Washington D.C. to Montgomery County, Maryland, on which life-expectancy rises a year and a half for every mile (Marmot 2004, 2). This leads to a third and final reason to care about health inequality. In some cases, what are seemingly examples of only inequalities in health are actually insufficiencies. Often critics of sufficientarianism underestimate the demandingness of the relevant threshold of biological and physical needs. On our own account, as we put it elsewhere, “if some faces an average life span of 55 years (as is the case, for example, in Malawi), they are clearly insufficiently well-off and under duress—regardless of the quality of their relations to other people” (Axelsen & Nielsen 2015, 421). So, regarding health capabilities and other capabilities related to biological and physical human needs seen in isolation only a sufficient—and not equal—level is required by justice. Equality, on the contrary, is merely instrumentally valuable due to the relational intertwinement between these capabilities and capabilities with strong positional aspects. In policy-making, then, these aspects must be kept apart if justice is to be attained. The second category of capabilities—related to fundamental interests of a human agent—is special. Like the biological and physical capabilities, the capabilities in this category such as affiliation, educational competence, critical reflection and normative evaluation are not intrinsically positional. That is, in contrast to capabilities related to fundamental interest of a 21 social being it is not true for these capabilities that whenever one person gets more capability, others are made worse off in an absolute sense. Consequently, sufficiency of capabilities related to fundamental interests of a human agent does not per se require an equal distribution for justice to be fulfilled. It is perfectly legitimate, for example, to hold that a society is sufficiently just when all have some reasonable level of education, a decent ground for affiliation, critical reflection and evaluation and so forth. These capabilities revolve around the importance of individual human autonomy—the ability to think critically, to evaluate normatively, and to set and pursue valuable goals for oneself—and as defenders of the value of autonomy have rightfully argued, sufficiency is the most plausible distributive ideal for such a value (Raz 1986; Dworkin 1988; Blake 2001, Nielsen 2015). On the other hand, the capabilities related to the fundamental interests of a human agent differ significantly from capabilities related to biological and physical needs in terms of the type of possible obstacles that may hinder the conversion of capability into achievement. These obstacles are recognized in the capability approach literature as conversion factors (Robeyns 2005). The achievement of functionings related to biological and physical need capabilities are influenced by personal conversion factors that are, in a way, internal to the capability. This includes factors such as metabolism, physical condition, security etc. where having the capability (say for health functioning) basically includes these factors. On the other hand, the effective opportunity for converting human agent capabilities (such as critical reflection and affiliation) into the related achieved functionings is often potentially obstructed by external factors. For example, a person’s opportunity for getting a meaningful job that is appropriate to her level and type of education is not only dependent on her personal capacities and acquired skills but also on competition from other human agents and social norms. Similarly, a person’s opportunity for 22 affiliation is deeply dependent on the social milieu and cultural environment and not only her own personal capacities. In sum, although capabilities related to the fundamental interests of a human agent are not intrinsically positional, the obstacles which may delimit people’s opportunity to succeed in these areas is very often externally defined and rooted in the social context. In both examples, then, access to some of the important functionings to which these capabilities are key is determined by the capability levels of others, and are, thus, partly positional. In other words, their value is often (at least partly) determined by how they are linked to other capabilities. We shall therefore call these quasi-positional capabilities. Based on this analysis of how to understand the distributional logics of the different types of capabilities, the question of how to obtain sufficientarian justice within this pluralist capabilitarian framework needs to be addressed. We suggest that justice as capabilitarian sufficiency entails the following requirements: (i) Indexing process: Any theory, social assessment or political arrangement that adhere to social justice should concentrate (only) on capabilities that are centrally important for people’s lives as opposed to maximizing or equalizing preference satisfaction, welfare, or wealth. Although subjective preferences are in themselves not relevant for the selection of capabilities, any legitimate indexing should safeguard people’s influence over the selection process, due to the intrinsic importance of the capability of personal choice. (ii) Capability typology: Any index of capabilities relevant for social justice would include three distinct categories of central capabilities: (1) Capabilities related to biological and physical human needs; (2) Capabilities related to fundamental interests of a human agent; and (3) Capabilities related to fundamental interests of a 23 social being. For justice to be fulfilled, a political arrangement must be sensitive to the different distributional logics of the distinct types of central capabilities. (iii) Non-positional logic: The first category of capabilities are non-positional—their absolute value for a particular person is independent of what other people have—and thus justice requires (only) that everyone is secured a decent level of all such capabilities (health, housing, security etc.). Importantly, however, their interconnection with capabilities with positional aspects may, nonetheless, require avoiding great inequalities in their distribution. (iv) Positional logic: The third category is positional—that is, the absolute value of these capabilities depends on other people’s capabilities—and thus justice requires that everyone enjoys a more or less equal share of these capabilities (political influence, societal status etc.). (v) Quasi-positional logic: The second category is quasi-positional—that is, these capabilities are not intrinsically positional, but important related functionings often involve obstacles from external social conversion factors with positional logics. In regards to these capabilities, justice requires that everyone is secured a sufficient level of all such capabilities (critical reflection, education, affiliation etc.). And, moreover, that no person is obstructed from converting these capabilities to their relevant achievements due to pressure from external factors. In the preceding sections, we have reformulated sufficientarian social justice enlightened by an overall typology of central capabilities. In this section, we have argued that bringing people above the threshold within a capability category may imply either an equal distribution or 24 bringing everyone above an absolute threshold and ignoring inequalities beyond this threshold, depending on the type of capability. More specifically, it depends on the empirical interconnections in play and whether the distribution of the capability is governed by positional logics. If this is the case, a person’s relative capability level determines their absolute level, and, thus, dictates whether they are sufficiently well-off. In other words, we affirm the negative thesis; that once people have sufficient capabilities in all these areas, inequalities are irrelevant to social justice. This pluralist view, we claim, seems in tune with how the requirements for living a flourishing life are normally judged, and joining it with the notion of positional goods gives intuitively appealing reasons for accepting the negative thesis for capabilitarians who hold that the human good is multifaceted. Conclusion Although the capability approach encompasses several relatively comprehensive and innovative accounts of social justice, most are still either undecided or underdeveloped when it comes to the issue of distributive justice. In this paper, we have outlined the sufficiency principle within a capabilitarian framework of social justice revolving around a categorization of central human capabilities that we believe most capabilitarians would accept. We have shown how the sufficiency principle should be interpreted when informed by the inherent pluralism entailed in the capability approach and argued that this pluralism serves as an argument for sufficiency; not against it. Furthermore, we have argued that what effectively determines the threshold of sufficiency varies according to the distributional logics within each category of capability, depending on the presence or absence of positional aspects for that particular capability. In other words, whereas social justice in regards to non-positional and quasi-positional capabilities 25 requires securing an adequate level for everyone, and protecting people from external pressure on their opportunity to succeed, social justice in regard to positional capabilities requires an equal distribution, but for sufficientarian (not egalitarian) reasons. This reasoning grounds the acceptance of the negative thesis of sufficientarianism. We conclude that this account of capabilitarian sufficiency shows much promise towards closing one of the central gaps still remaining in the development of the capability approach within the field of social justice. References Alkire, S. 2002. Valuing Freedoms: Sen's Capability Approach and Poverty Reduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Alkire, S. 2005. ”Why the Capability Approach?” Journal of Human Development 6 (1): 115- 135. Anderson, E. 1999. “What is the point of equality?” Ethics 109: 287-337. Axelsen, D. and L. Nielsen 2015. “Sufficiency as Freedom from Duress.” The Journal of Political Philosophy 13 (4):406-426. Banerjee, A. V., and E. Duflo. 2011. Poor Economics: A Radical Rethinking of the Way to Fight Global Poverty. New York: Public Affairs. Blake, M. 2001. “Distributive Justice, State Coercion, and Autonomy”, Philosophy & Public Affairs 30 (3): 257-296. Brighouse, H., and A. Swift. 2006. “Equality, Priority, and Positional Goods.” Ethics 116 (3): 471-497. Casal, P. 2007. “Why Sufficiency Is Not Enough.” Ethics 117 (2): 296-326. 26 Crisp, R. 2003. “Equality, Priority, and Compassion.” Ethics 113: 745-763. Dworkin, G. 1988. The Theory and Practice pf Autonomy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Frankfurt, H. 1987. ”Equality as a Moral Ideal.” Ethics 98: 21-43. Frankfurt, H. 1997. “Equality & Respect.” Social Research 64 (1): 3-15. Huseby, R. 2010. “Sufficiency: Restated and Defended.” The Journal of Political Philosophy 18(2): 178-197. Marmot, M. 2004. Status Syndrome. London: Bloomsbury. Miller, D. 2007. National Responsibility and Global Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Nielsen, L. 2015. “Sufficiency Grounded as Sufficiently Free: A Reply to Shlomi Segall”, Journal of Applied Philosophy, early online view, DOI: 10.1111/japp.12159. Nussbaum, M. C. 2000. Women and Human Development. New York: Cambridge University Press. Nussbaum, M. C. 2006. Frontiers of Justice. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. Nussbaum, M. C. 2011. Creating Capabilities – The Human Development Approach. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. Parfit, D. 1997. “Equality and Priority.” Ratio 10 (3): 202-221. Raz, J. 1986. The Morality of Freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Richardson, H. S. 2006. “Rawlsian Social-contract Theory and the Severely Disabled,” The Journal of Ethics 10: 419–462. 27 Robeyns, I. 2005. “The Capability Approach: A Theoretical Survey.” Journal of Human Development 6 (1): 93-117. Robeyns, I. 2011. “Sen’s Capability Approach and Gender Inequality: Selecting Relevant Capabilities.” Feminist Economics 9 (2-3): 61-92. Sen, A. 1992. Inequality Reexamined. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Sen, A. 1993. “Capability and Well-being.” In Nussbaum M. C., and Sen A. (eds.), The Quality of Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 30-53. Sen, A. 1997. “Maximization and the Act of Choice.” Econometrica 65 (4): 745-779. Sen, A. 1999. Development as Freedom. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Sen, A. 2005. “Human Rights and Capabilities.” Journal of Human Development 6 (2): 151-166. Sen, A. 2009. The Idea of Justice. Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. Shields, L. 2012. “The Prospects for Sufficientarianism.” Utilitas 24 (1): 101-117. Shue, H. 1996. Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence, and U.S. Foreign Policy – Second Edition. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Temkin, L. 2003. “Equality, Priority, or what?” Economics and Philosophy 19: 61-87. Vallentyne, P. 2005. “Debate: Capabilities versus Opportunities for Well-being.” Journal of Political Philosophy 13 (3): 359-371. Wilkinson, R. and K. Pickett. 2010. The Spirit Level: Why Equality is Better for Everyone. London: Penguin Books. 28 i And indeed, poor people often choose taste and variation over calories even when malnourished, and in desperate need of calories. See Banerjee, and Duflo (2011, ch. 2). ii Although, Anderson’s preferred ideal is egalitarian in the sense that it claims we should aim for a society of equals, this is entirely compatible with saying that everyone should have enough distributively and be treated with a high level of respect (although not necessarily be treated in the same way). Axelsen_Capabilitarian sufficiency_2016_cover Axelsen_Capabilitarian sufficiency_2016_author work_ln56cwsp7ffppl4wxeq7osqfuu ---- ON THE JUSTICE OF DECISION RULES∗ JOSE APESTEGUIA†, MIGUEL A. BALLESTER‡, AND ROSA FERRER§ Abstract. Which decision rules are the most efficient? Which are the best in terms of maximin, or maximax? We study these questions for the case of a group of individuals faced with a choice from a set of alternatives. First, we show that the set of optimal decision rules is well-defined, particularly simple, and well-known: the class of scoring rules. Second, we provide the optimal decision rules for the three different ideals of justice under consideration: utilitarianism (efficiency), maximin, and maximax. We show that plurality, arguably the most widely used voting sys- tem, is optimal in terms of maximax, while the best way to achieve maximin is by means of negative voting, and the optimal utilitarian decision rule depends on the culture of the society. We then provide the mapping between cultures and optimal decision rules. Keywords: Decision rules, Scoring Rules, Voting, Utilitarianism, Maximin, Maxi- max. JEL classification numbers: D00, D63, D71, D72. 1. Introduction Should I implement a plurality voting rule if I aim to maximize efficiency? If I am persuaded by the maximin ideal of justice, should I implement the Borda count? What should I use if it is maximax that I wish to optimize? These are the type of questions addressed in this paper. Our aim is to identify the best decision rules in terms of these three ideals of justice. In our setting, individuals’ preferences are cardinal and interpersonally comparable utility random variables. The realization of the individual utility values depends on the culture of the society, which is simply a probability distribution over the range of utility intensities. We consider three prominent ideals of justice defined in cardinal Date: September, 2008. ∗ We thank Toni Calvo, Gabor Lugosi, Larry Samuelson, and Rann Smorodinsky for valu- able comments. Financial support by the Spanish Commission of Science and Technology CICYT (SEJ2006-11510, SEJ2005-01481/ECON), the Barcelona GSE research network, and the Generalitat de Catalunya is gratefully acknowledged. † Universitat Pompeu Fabra. E-mail: jose.apesteguia@upf.edu. ‡ Universitat Autonoma de Barcelona. E-mail: miguelangel.ballester@uab.es. § Vanderbilt University. E-mail: rosa.ferrer@vanderbilt.edu. 1 2 terms: utilitarianism (or efficiency), maximin, and maximax. In short, utilitarian- ism evaluates an alternative in terms of the average of the individual utility values. The maximin principle disregards the utility values of the most favored individuals to evaluate an alternative on the basis of the utility value of the worst-off agent. In contrast with maximin, the maximax rule focuses on the best-off individuals. Maxi- max as an ideal of justice may appear a mere formal curiosity. However, we will see that, because of its close connection to plurality voting, the maximax principle plays a more important role in democratic political institutions than might be expected. In our model, n individuals must choose an alternative from a set of k ≥ 3 alter- natives. Decision rules serve precisely this purpose. A decision rule transforms the ordinal preferences of the individuals into a selection of alternatives. We impose no restriction on the possible set of decision rules, other than assuming that it uses the actual ordinal preferences of the individuals. The question arises of what the optimal decision rules are in terms of a particular cardinal ideal of justice. That is, we explore the connection between a given ideal of justice and different decision rules, with the aim of identifying those that best serve the pursued ideal of justice. There are different options for measuring decision rule performance. A natural index can be obtained by evaluating decision rules in terms of their expected attainable value for a given ideal of justice. Another index emerges by judging decision rules on the basis of the probability of their selecting the best alternative for a given theory of justice. Yet a third possibility is to measure the probability of avoiding the worst alternatives. The three criteria approach the same problem from different angles, and hence in principle complement each other. It could be argued that the first index adopts a risk-neutral approach to measure the success of decision rules, while the second and third indices could be understood as representative of risk-loving and risk-averse positions, respectively. Firstly, we show that a particularly prominent class of decision rules emerges as optimal: the class of scoring rules. A scoring rule is a vector of fixed points that individuals assign to the different alternatives. The plurality scoring rule, the negative scoring rule and Borda’s scoring rule are especially salient. This result significantly restricts the class of decision rules from which to seek the optimal ones. A further point is that scoring rules are relatively easy to implement and widely used. Secondly, our results indicate that the message for each ideal of justice is robust across indices. That is, what matters is the nature of the ideal of justice, not the particular way of measuring decision rule performance. Thirdly, we provide the optimal decision rules for the three ideals of justice. In utilitarian terms, we show that there is a mapping from the culture of the society to the optimal decision rule. Moreover, we find the exact shape of the optimal decision rule, conditional on the culture of the society. We then illustrate the result with a number of examples. In particular, we show that for a range of cultures satisfying 3 a certain regularity condition, a prominent scoring rule emerges as optimal: Borda. When the culture follows the normal distribution, the optimal decision rule for util- itarianism is not Borda but a scoring rule where the differences in the values given to consecutive alternatives is a symmetric and strictly convex function. That is, with the normal distribution, the optimal scoring rule strongly discriminates between the very best alternatives and also between the very worst alternatives. Alternatives in between are treated as almost alike. We explore the connection between the optimal utilitarian decision rule and other prominent cultures, such as the exponential or the logistic distribution. In contrast to utilitarianism, maximax offers a unique optimal decision rule for every possible culture. It proves to be a remarkably important decision rule: plurality. Although plurality is probably the most widely used voting system in the democratic world, our results show that, instead of maximizing efficiency or the well-being of the worst-off agents in a society, plurality maximizes the well-being of the best-off, a property that may be considered of questionable merit. Finally, maximin is best approached with the negative scoring rule. Given the link between plurality and maximax, it is not surprising that negative, the symmetric scoring rule to plurality, is the best decision rule in terms of maximin, which can be shown to be in a way symmetric to maximax. Interestingly, the results for the three ideals of justice point to the three best-known scoring rules: plurality, Borda, and negative. We are certainly not the first to evaluate decision rules. There is a large and still growing literature examining decision rules in terms of the properties they satisfy. In other words, decision rules are judged on the basis of their capacity to meet cer- tain desirable properties such as anonymity, independence of irrelevant alternatives, strategy-proofness, consistency of the social preference ordering, Pareto-dominance, path-independence, probability of selecting the Condorcet winner, etc.1 In this paper, we focus not on the specific properties that voting systems may or may not satisfy, but on how well they perform in terms of an ideal of justice. If there is agreement over which ideal of justice is to be pursued, it seems much more relevant to evaluate voting systems on the basis of how well they serve that ideal, than it is to calculate the probability of their electing the Condorcet winner, for example. In other words, in this paper we shift the decision rule evaluation criterion from an ordinal to a cardinal approach. The problem therefore reduces to inferring the relevant utility intensities from ordinal rankings. There is very little work on evaluating decision rules on the basis of some cardinal theory of justice. Notable exceptions are the early simulation studies of Bordley (1983) and Merrill (1984), and the theoretical work of Weber (1978). Bordley and 1Early studies are Brams and Fishburn (1978), Caplin and Nalebuff (1988), DeMeyer and Plott (1970), and Nurmi (1983). See also Benoit and Kornhauser (2007), Dasgupta and Maskin (2008), Gehrlein (1997), Levin and Nalebuff (1995), Myerson (2002), and Saari (1999). 4 Merrill use simulations to analyze the efficiency of different voting systems, including plurality and Borda. Consistent with our results, they show that plurality is easily outperformed in utilitarian terms by other decision rules. Weber (1978) studies the performance of scoring rules for the case of utilitarianism and for cultures following the uniform distribution. He shows that, asymptotically, Borda is the best scoring rule in this case. This, again, is consistent with our results. In another related strand of literature, there are papers that study how to select a voting rule in a constitutional setting where there are two options, the status quo and a second alternative, and individual preferences are uncertain. A voting rule is characterized by the number of votes needed to accept the second alternative over the status quo. The papers that comprise this literature examine issues such as which voting rules maximize efficiency, which are self-stable, how to weight votes in heterogeneous contexts, self-enforcement voting rules, etc. For examples in this vein, see Rae (1969), Barbera and Jackson (2004, 2006), Maggi and Morelli (2006) and papers cited therein. Finally, there is a growing literature addressing the question of the transmission of utility intensities in collective decision problems (see Casella, 2005; Jackson and Sonnenschein, 2007; and Hortala-Vallve, 2007). The innovation of these papers is to consider a collective decision situation problem repeated over T times and endow individuals with a maximum number of votes to allocate over the T problems. By so doing, individuals may transmit utility intensities. The remainder of the paper is organized as follows. Section 2 introduces in detail the setting in which we will be working. Sections 3, 4, and 5 study the cases of utilitarianism, maximax and maximin, respectively. Finally, Section 6 presents some conclusions. All the proofs are given in Appendix A. 2. Environment Let N be a finite set of individuals with cardinality n ≥ 2 and K the set of alternatives with cardinality k ≥ 3. Typical elements of N are denoted by i and j and those of K are denoted by l,h and q. We then say that a society is composed of n individuals with preferences over k alternatives. To address the question of finding the best ordinal decision rule to approach each given ideal of justice, we first present the cardinal environment (utilities and ideals of justice), then the ordinal setting (decision rules and ordinal preferences), and then the one that connects the two worlds (indices evaluating the success of a decision rule in terms of an ideal of justice). 2.1. Cardinal Preferences. Individual preferences over the set of alternatives are cardinal, interpersonally comparable utility random variables in the [0, 1] interval. Uli is the random variable representing the cardinal utility of individual i for alternative 5 l. We adopt the convention that subindices refer to individuals and superindices refer to alternatives. Let culture C be the probability distribution from which the cardinal individual utility values are drawn. We consider cultures with continuous probability distributions on [0, 1]. Hence, the probability that Uli takes a particular value on [0, 1] is zero, and then the probability of ties (i.e., of individual i being indifferent between two alternatives) is also zero.2 Moreover, we assume that variables {Uli}i∈N,l∈K are iid. We say that a culture is symmetric whenever its density function is symmetric. Given the random variables U1i ,U 2 i , . . . ,U k i , the order statistics U (1) i ≤ U (2) i ≤ ···≤ U (k) i are also random variables, defined by sorting the realizations of U (1) i ≤ U (2) i ≤ ··· ≤ U(k)i in increasing order of magnitude. U (l) i denotes the l-th order statistic of individual i, representing the utility value for individual i of that alternative having l− 1 alternatives with lower utility values. Analogously, we will be using order statistics given an alternative l. Consider the collection of random variables Ul1,U l 2, . . . ,U l n, and arrange them in order of magnitude by denoting Ul(1) ≤ U l (2) ≤ ··· ≤ U l (n). Here U l (i) denotes the utility value of the i-th order statistic for alternative l, representing the utility value of l for that individual who ranks l higher than exactly i−1 individuals. A Social Welfare Function SWF is a mapping W from [0, 1]n×k to [0, 1]k, where W l(Ul) ∈ [0, 1] denotes the social value of alternative l, given the realization of random variables Ul = (Ul1, . . . ,U l n). 3 The three SWFs we consider here are utilitarianism, maximin, and maximax. Utilitarianism evaluates an alternative by taking the average of individual cardinal utilities. Formally, a SWF is utilitarian if W = WUT with W lUT (U l) = ∑n i=1 U l i/n. The maximin principle evaluates an alternative on the basis of the utility value of the worst-off agent, disregarding any other utility value. In other words, a SWF is of the maximin type if W = WMN with W l MN (U l) = Ul(1). Consider also the maximax rule. In contrast to maximin, the maximax rule focuses on the best-off individuals. That is, a SWF is of the maximax type if W = WMX with W lMX(U l) = Ul(n). 2.2. Ordinal Preferences. The following describes the ordinal rankings of the in- dividuals over the set of alternatives. M is an n × k matrix with properties: (1) mli ∈ {1, . . . ,k}, and (2) mli 6= mhi for all i ∈ N and for all l,h ∈ K, l 6= h. Entry mli denotes the position of alternative l in the preferences of individual i, where the higher mli is, the higher alternative l is ranked by individual i. 4 Mi denotes the i- th row of matrix M. That is, Mi represents the ordinal preferences of individual i. Ml denotes the l-th column of matrix M, representing the ordinal preferences of all 2Given our assumption that cultures are continuous probability distributions on [0, 1], all our results naturally extend to other ranges such as (0, 1), (−∞,∞), or [0,∞). 3Throughout the paper we use the terms “social welfare function” and “ideal of justice” indistinctly. 4Note that given the assumptions on continuous probability distributions, there are no ties, and hence property (2) above follows. 6 individuals with respect to alternative l. The collection of all possible matrices M is denoted by M. Finally, by l(h) we refer to the number of individuals that place alternative l exactly above h− 1 alternatives. That is, l(h) = |{i ∈ N : mli = h}|. A multi-valued decision rule f is a correspondence from M to K. Denote by F the set of all decision rules f. That is, a decision rule takes ordinal information on preferences as input to determine a set of alternatives as social choice. We assume that f uses true information. That is, the particular matrix M over which f is applied is assumed to be known. Scoring rules are a particularly interesting class of decision rules. They are typically simple to implement in practice and they encompass a number of widely-used decision rules. Formally, a scoring rule S can be represented by a vector S ∈ [0, 1]k, with Sl denoting the strength of an individual’s vote for whichever alternative she ranks higher than exactly l − 1 alternatives. We normalize strength of vote by assigning a value 1 to the best alternative, and a value 0 to the worst. That is, we set Sk = 1 and S1 = 0. Note that this normalization of the extreme values is without loss of generality. We denote by S(M) ⊆ K the set of alternatives selected by scoring rule S with preferences M. An alternative l is selected by scoring rule S when M, if l gets the highest number of points across individuals when ordinal preferences are M. The especially salient scoring rules are plurality, Borda, and negative. A scoring rule is plurality if S = SPl with S l Pl = 0 for every l < k. It is negative if S = SNg with SlNg = 1 for every l > 1, and it is Borda if S = SBd with S l Bd = l−1 k−1 for every l. 2.3. Cardinal and Ordinal Preferences: Evaluating Decision Rules. We will be using three different indices to evaluate the performance of alternatives in terms of the ideals of justice under consideration. The first, which we denote by the α-index, judges an alternative l on the basis of the expected value that l provides in terms of an ideal of justice W. That is, αlW (M) = E[W l(Ul) | M]. Recall that W lUT (U l) = ∑n i=1 U l i n , W lMN (U l) = Ul(1), and W l MX(U l) = Ul(n). For the case of utilitarianism and given ordinal preferences M, alternative l is better than alternative q in terms of the α-index, if the expected average utility value of l is larger than the expected average value of q. Therefore, the aim is to find decision rules that select alternatives with the highest expected average utility value. Now consider maximin. Then, for a given M, alternative l is better than alternative q in terms of the α-index, if l provides a higher expected value of the lowest order statistic, than q. Finally, l is better than q for maximax in terms of the α-index, if l provides a higher expected value of the highest order statistic than q, given ordinal preferences M. 7 The β-index, on the other hand, measures for a given SWF W, the probability of an alternative l being optimal : βlW (M) = P(W l(Ul) ≥ Wh(Uh) for all h ∈ K \{l} | M). Instead of looking to the expected value of an alternative, the β-index considers the probability of that alternative providing the highest social welfare value, given ordinal preferences M. Under utilitarianism, maximin, and maximax, we will be talking about the probability of selecting those alternatives that give the highest average utility value, the highest value among the first order statistics, and the highest value among the highest order statistics, respectively. Finally, for a given SWF W the γ-index evaluates alternatives in terms of the probability of not choosing the worst alternative: γlW (M) = 1 −P(W l(Ul) < Wh(Uh) for all h ∈ K \{l} | M) = P(W l(Ul) ≥ Wh(Uh) for some h ∈ K \{l} | M). The three indices are different in nature. It could be argued that the α-index adopts a risk neutral approach to measure the success of decision rules. Indices β and γ, however, could be understood as adopting risk-loving and risk-averse positions, respectively. Indices and ideals of justice are intimately linked. There is a natural link between utilitarianism and the α-index, between maximax and the β-index, and between max- imin and the γ-index. It is in fact the case that these natural links translate into ana- lytical tractability. We will see that utilitarianism is best approached analytically by the α-index, while the β-index is poorly suited to the formal study of utilitarianism. With respect to maximax, in contrast, great analytical progress can be made with the β-index, but the tractability of maximax with regard to α becomes complex. For intuition, consider for instance the α-index of an alternative l in utilitarian terms. The value of the α-index is the average of the expected value of the different order statistics that make up alternative l. In terms of maximax (and similarly for max- imin), one has to obtain the expected value of the highest order statistic of l. This is a challenge. If there is an individual who ranks l as her best alternative, then this individual is a good candidate to represent the highest order statistic of l. However, if for example there are many individuals who ranks l as their second best alterna- tive, then it is likely that the highest order statistic of l is among the latter group of individuals. Thus, there is a complex dependent structure that forces consideration of the interrelation between the random utility variables of all the individuals in the society for all the alternatives. An XW -optimal decision rule, with XW = {αW ,βW ,γW}, is a decision rule f that always selects alternatives with the largest X-index for ideal of justice W. That is, 8 f is XW -optimal decision rule if for all M ∈M: l ∈ f(M) ⇒ XlW (M) ≥ X h W (M) for all h ∈ K. It is straightforward to see that, given an XW -optimal decision rule f, any other decision rule in the family δ(f) = {g ∈F : ∅ 6= g(M) ⊆ f(M) for all M ∈M} is also an XW -optimal decision rule. In order to characterize the set of XW -optimal decision rules, it is sufficient to identify the maximum XW -optimal f. We will say that f is the maximum XW -optimal decision rule if whenever f and g are XW -optimal, then it must be that g ∈ δ(f). 3. Utilitarianism We first show that for every n×k society and every culture, the optimal decision rule to maximize the utilitarian expected value is a scoring rule. This is good news. It implies that if the interest is to maximize the expected value of utilitarianism, it is advisable to implement a scoring rule, which is a relatively simple decision rule. Furthermore, we provide the exact form of the optimal scoring rule, conditional on the culture under consideration. More specifically, a culture determines the expected value of the order statistics, which in turn determines the optimal value of the scoring rule. Knowledge of the culture of the society provides information on the expected value of the order statistics, which can be used to design the optimal scoring rule. In particular, we show that for a range of cultures with symmetric density functions, a prominent scoring rule emerges as the maximum optimal: Borda. The intuition goes as follows. The jumps in strength that Borda assigns to consecutive order statistics are constant. Hence, cultures in which the expected value of the order statistics has this property are the most closely linked to Borda. Also, when the culture follows the normal distribution, we show that the optimal decision rule is a scoring rule where the differences in the values given to consecutive alternatives is a symmetric convex func- tion. That is, under the normal distribution, it is optimal to discriminate between the very best alternatives and also between the very worst alternatives, and less impor- tant to discriminate between the intermediate alternatives. Interestingly, when the culture of the society follows a Cauchy distribution then the pattern becomes even more pronounced. In this case, the optimal scoring rule tends to discriminate be- tween the very best alternative and the very worst alternative, treating all remaining alternatives in almost the same manner. We then turn to the analysis of the β- and γ-indices. The β-index (as well as the γ) is less well suited than the α-index to the analytical study of utilitarianism. The source of difficulty lies in the dependency across alternatives. To determine the probability of an alternative being the utilitarian alternative, it is necessary to take the whole society into account. This dependency drastically limits the analytical tractability of utilitarianism in terms of the β-index. For this reason, we begin with 9 the formal study of a small society, a 2×3 society, for a complete range of cultures with symmetric density functions, and then we run a set of simulations to approach larger societies. Our analytical results for small societies and the computational analysis for larger societies provide analogous results as those obtained in the formal study of the α-index. This is reassuring since it indicates that there is a great deal of consistency across indices. What matters is the social welfare function, not the particular way of measuring success. Finally, our analysis of the γ-index exploits a symmetry relation with the β-index, allowing us to immediately reach the same conclusions as those reached with the β-index. We organize the study of utilitarianism by first giving the general results obtained with the α-index, and we then turn to the study of the β- and γ-indices. 3.1. The αUT -index: Evaluating Decision Rules in terms of Expected Value. Theorem 3.1 below provides the main result for utilitarianism. It first identifies a scor- ing rule as the maximum optimal decision rule, and then it characterizes the exact shape of the scoring rule. Importantly, it does so for any n × k society and for any culture. Theorem 3.1. For n×k societies and for every culture, the maximum αUT -optimal rule is a scoring rule with S∗l = E[U(l)]−E[U(1)] E[U(k)]−E[U(1)] , l ∈{1, . . . ,k}. Theorem 3.1 shows that there is a mapping from the culture of the society to the optimal decision rule. A culture determines the first moment of the order statistics, and this in turn characterizes the optimal decision rule. This raises the question of what the optimal decision rules of especially prominent cultures are like. The follow- ing corollary represents a first illustration. Corollary 3.2. The maximum αUT -optimal rule is Borda: • For n×k societies and for every culture such that E[U(l+1)]−E[U(l)] = c, with 1 ≤ l ≤ n− 1. • In particular for the uniform distribution. • For n× 3 societies and for every culture with a symmetric density function. Corollary 3.2 points to a prominent decision rule, Borda, as the optimal rule for a wide range of cultures with density functions satisfying a regularity condition. But there are many other relevant cultures for which to obtain the optimal scoring rule. Consider the normal distribution, for example. The expected value of the order sta- tistics from the normal distribution are tabularized (see, e.g., Teichroew, 1956). From 10 inspection of these values, it immediately emerges that the αUT -optimal decision rule in this case is a scoring rule where S∗l+1 −S∗l is a symmetric and convex function. A more extreme version of the above emerges when considering the Cauchy distribution (see, e.g., Barnett (1966) for the expected values of the Cauchy order statistics). In the latter case, the optimal scoring rule tends to discriminate only between the very best alternative, the very worst alternative and all the rest. We can further apply our Theorem 3.1 to other classes of probability distributions via known results in the literature of order statistics. By way of illustration consider the following class of probability distributions F (see Kamps, 1991, 1992; see also Balakrishnan and Sultan 1998): d dt F−1(t) = 1 d tp(1 − t)q−p−1, t ∈ (0, 1), where p and q are integers and d > 0. The values of parameters p and q determine the probability distribution. For example, if p = q = 0 we get the expo- nential distribution, if p = q = −1 we get the logistic distribution, if p > −1 and q = p + 1 we get the power function, etc. We can then establish the following result for this class of probability distributions. Theorem 3.3. For n × k societies and for the class of cultures F , the maximum αUT -optimal rule is a scoring rule with S∗l = ∑l h=2 E[U (h)] − E[U(h−1)]∑k h=2 E[U(h)] − E[U(h−1)] , l ∈{1, . . . ,k}, with E[U(h)] − E[U(h−1)] = ( k h−1) (h+p)(k+qh+p) . The introduction of the values of the parameters into the equations of Theorem 3.3 immediately gives the optimal scoring rule. By way of illustration, let k = 3. It is immediate that when there are three alternatives, the optimal scoring rule is well-defined by the value assigned to the middle alternative. Corollary 3.4. For n × 3 societies and for the class of cultures F , the maximum αUT -optimal rule is a scoring rule with S ∗2 = 1−p+q 3+q , where p and q are integers. The above corollary provides the optimal scoring rule contingent on the values of parameters p and q, and hence contingent on the culture of the society. 11 3.2. The βUT -index: Evaluating Decision Rules in terms of the Probability of Selecting an Optimal Alternative. Due to the analytical complexity of the study of utilitarianism through the lens of the βUT -index, we begin with the formal study of a small society, a 2×3 society, for a complete range of cultures with symmetric density functions, and we then run a set of simulations to approach larger societies. In societies with n = 2 and k = 3 there are 5 different scoring rules, since every S2 ∈ (0, 1/2) represents the same scoring rule, and similarly every S2 ∈ (1/2, 1) also represents the same scoring rule.5 Hence, the set of different scoring rules when n = 2 and k = 3 comprises plurality with S2Pl = 0, Borda with S 2 Bd = 1/2, negative with S2Ng = 1, an explosion rule with any value S 2 Ex ∈ (1/2, 1), and an implosion rule with any value S2Im ∈ (0, 1/2). We study a collection of cultures with symmetric density functions. Take the para- bolic function f(x) = ax2 +bx+c, with x ∈ [0, 1]. Now, in order for f(x) to represent a symmetric density function it must be the case that a = −b = −(1−c), with c tak- ing values in [0, 3]. Note that the c = 1 case corresponds to the uniform distribution. Values of c ∈ [0, 1) correspond to strictly concave density functions. That is, lower values of c represent higher levels of consensus on the evaluation of an alternative. Finally, values of c ∈ (1, 3] correspond to strictly convex density functions. Hence, higher values of c represent higher levels of extremism. Theorem 3.5. For 2 × 3 societies and for any culture with a symmetric parabolic function: (1) The maximum βUT -optimal rule is the implosion scoring rule. (2) The intersection between the alternatives selected by Borda and those selected by the maximum βUT -optimal rule is always non-empty. The analysis of the 2 × 3 case shows that any scoring rule with S2 ∈ (0, 1/2) is βUT -optimal. Moreover, it also shows that although Borda is not βUT -optimal, it comes close to being so. For every type of society M, the alternatives selected by Borda and implosion coincide, except for one (which in the proof of Theorem 3.5 we call societies of type 4) where Borda randomizes between the 3 alternatives while implosion randomizes between 2 alternatives. We extend the study of the βUT -optimal decision rule by using computational methods. We generate random cardinal societies from three different probability distributions: the uniform distribution on the interval [0, 1], the standard normal distribution on the interval (−∞,∞), and the exponential distribution on the interval [0,∞). We study societies of 2, 3, 5, 10 and 100 individuals with preferences over 3, 4, 5 and 7 alternatives. The technical details are contained in Appendix B. 5We say that two scoring rules S and S′ are the same if S(M) = S′(M) for all M. 12 The main conclusion of the computational analysis is very clear. The results across probability distributions and sizes of societies are fully in line with the analytical results we presented for the case of the αUT -index. That is, for each of the three probability distributions and sizes of societies scrutinized, the scoring rule providing the highest βUT -value is the corresponding one as stated in Theorem 3.1. In particular, for the uniform distribution the highest βUT -value is given by Borda; for the normal distribution it is given by a scoring rule where S∗l+1 −S∗l is a symmetric and convex function; and finally for the exponential distribution, the highest βUT -value is given by a scoring rule where S∗l+1 −S∗l grows exponentially.6 3.3. The γUT -index: Evaluating Decision Rules in terms of the Probabil- ity of Not Choosing the Worst Alternative. It is not difficult to appreciate that for utilitarianism and symmetry of the culture C, the γ-index is symmetric to the β-index in the following sense: take a society {Uli}i∈N,l∈K, and let l be an al- ternative giving the highest utilitarian value. Write the following symmetric society {U ′li }i∈N,l∈K with U ′l i = 1 −Ulσ(i) where σ(i) = n− i + 1. It follows that alternative l in society {U ′li }i∈N,l∈K is one of the worst alternatives in utilitarian terms. Then, the analytical and simulation results that we obtained for the β-index and for symmetric cultures can be extrapolated to the case of the γ-index. To complete the picture, we run an extra set of simulations for the exponential distribution, an asymmetric distri- bution, that points to, once again, that the particular index to measure performance is not essential (see Appendix B). We may conclude, therefore, that at least for the cases computationally scrutinized, the optimal decision rules in terms of γUT are well captured in Theorem 3.1. 4. Maximax We start the analysis of maximax by showing formally that for any n×k society and for any culture, the maximum optimal decision rule in terms of the probability of selecting the maximax alternatives is a scoring rule. In fact, it is a particularly simple and widely used scoring rule: plurality. The intuition is very simple. Maxi- max evaluates an alternative l in terms of that individual that most values alternative l. It is very likely that such an individual ranks l as her most preferred alternative. Consequently, those alternatives that are considered by the highest number of indi- viduals as best are the most likely maximax alternatives. Plurality selects precisely these alternatives. The analytical and computational study of the two other indices reinforce the connection between plurality and maximax. 6For the sake of comparison, Appendix B reports the βU T -values of the optimal scoring rules as predicted by Theorem 3.1, together with the three prominent scoring rules–plurality, Borda, and negative–for each of the societies and cultures under scrutiny. 13 We start the analysis of the maximax case by first giving the general results reached with the β-index and then we turn to the study of the α and γ-indices. 4.1. The βMX-index: Evaluating Decision Rules in terms of the Probability of Selecting an Optimal Alternative. Theorem 4.1 below shows that something as simple as the plurality decision rule offers the highest probability of selecting the maximax alternative. Theorem 4.1 does not assume any particular probability distri- bution over the individual utility values, or any society size. Theorem 4.1. For n×k societies and for any culture, the maximum βMX-optimal rule is the plurality scoring rule. Corollary 4.2 reinforces the role of plurality in the maximax ideal of justice. It shows that, as the society grows, plurality is the unique optimal scoring rule. Corollary 4.2. For any given k and for any culture, when n tends to infinity plural- ity is the only scoring rule in the set of βMX-optimal scoring rules. Theorem 4.1 and Corollary 4.2 give a very clear message: if the interest is in maximax, then the decision rule that should be implemented is as simple as plurality, irrespective of the culture and size of the society. 4.2. The αMX-index: Evaluating Decision Rules in terms of Expected Value. We start the analysis of maximax in terms of the α-index by studying the contribu- tion made to the maximax expected value of an alternative l by adding one extra best order statistic, as opposed to the value added by a second best order statistic, when the culture follows the uniform distribution. We explore the extreme case where everybody ranks alternative l as the best. It is in this case that the extra expected maximax value of adding one best alternative is intuitively the smallest. We show that, even in this case, the contribution made to the expected maximax value by adding one extra best order statistic is of a higher order of magnitude than that made by adding a second best order statistic. Then, plurality is the clear candidate to be the optimal maximax decision rule in terms of the α-index, since it gives weight only to the best random variables. Consider the n×k society M such that mli = k for every i ∈{1, . . . ,n}. That is, all n individuals in society M rank alternative l as the best. Consider also the following two (n + 1)×k societies, M ′ and M, such that m′li = k for every i ∈{1, . . . ,n,n + 1}, and mli = k for every i ∈ {1, . . . ,n,n + 1} \ {j} and mlj = k − 1. In M ′, all n + 1 14 individuals rank l as the best alternative, while in M, there are n individuals who rank l as best, and one that ranks l as second best. Now, taking the n × k society M as the baseline, we ask what is the marginal contribution to the l-th maximax expected value of adding one extra individual who ranks l as best (society M ′). Also, we wonder about the marginal contribution of adding one extra individual who ranks l as second-best (society M). Denote these marginal contributions by ∆ (k) n and ∆ (k−1) n , where ∆ (k) n = E[Ul(n+1)|M ′l] − E[Ul(n)|M l] and ∆ (k−1) n = E[Ul(n+1)|M l ] − E[Ul(n)|M l]. The ratio ∆ (k) n ∆ (k−1) n represents the ratio of the marginal contributions of an extra order statistic in the top positions k and k − 1. Lemma 4.3 below shows that, for the uniform distribution, when l(k) = n, the ad- ditional expected value provided by one extra order statistic in the same position k is considerably higher than that provided by one extra order statistic in position k−1. Lemma 4.3. For n×k societies and for the uniform distribution, ∆ (k) n ∆ (k−1) n = k(n+1) k−1 . Intuitively the situation where everybody ranks l as best is the worst-case scenario for the expected marginal contribution of adding one extra individual who rank l the best alternative. Even in this case, Lemma 4.3 shows that the order of magnitude in the expected maximax value of an extra best random variable is considerably higher than that of an extra second best random variable. This clearly points to plurality as the candidate for the optimal maximax decision rule. Plurality gives weight only to best random variables, and hence selects alternatives with the highest number of best random variables. In the context of n individuals and 3 alternatives, and for the uniform distribu- tion, Proposition 4.4 below first provides the exact formula for the computation of the maximax expected value of any alternative l. Then, it shows that only under extreme circumstances does plurality prove not to be the αMX-optimal decision rule. Proposition 4.4. For n× 3 societies and for the uniform distribution, (1) E[Ul(n) | M] = ∑l(2) a=0 ∑l(1) b=0 ∑3b c=0 ( l(2) a )( l(1) b )( 3b c ) (−1)a+b+c3l(2)−a2a 3l (3)+2l(2)+a+c 3l(3)+2l(2)+a+c+1 (2) Let h be an αMX-optimal alternative and let p ∈ SPl(M)\{h}. Then, M must satisfy that either (a) h(3) = p(3) and h(2) ≥ p(2), or (b) h(3) = p(3) − 1 and h(2) > n−1 2 Proposition 4.4 shows that plurality is very difficult to beat in terms of its capacity to optimize the maximax expected value. The plurality alternative can be surpassed 15 by another alternative in terms of αMX if about the same people rank it as the best alternative and (many) more people rank it as second-best. Clearly, these are low- probability events, and hence plurality is very likely to be the αMX-optimal decision rule. In accordance with the above, the computational studies for the uniform, normal, and exponential distributions show that, for every single size of society scrutinized, plurality or a scoring rule in the neighborhood of plurality are always the αMX-optimal decision rule among the set of scoring rules evaluated (see Appendix B for details). 4.3. The γMX-index: Evaluating Decision Rules in terms of the Probability of Not Choosing the Worst Alternative. We start with the characterization of a small society. Theorem 4.5. For 2 × 3 societies and for any culture with a symmetric parabolic function: (1) Implosion is a γMX-optimal decision rule. (2) The intersection between the alternatives selected by plurality and those selected by the maximum γMX-optimal decision rule is always non-empty. Note that implosion is not the maximum γMX-optimal decision rule since, in soci- eties where the two individuals share the same ranking over the alternatives, implosion selects the single best alternative, instead of the two better alternatives. However, it is not difficult to see that, for general n×k societies, plurality is the natural candidate to select γMX-optimal alternatives. Below, in Proposition 4.6, we show that, for any n × k society and for any culture, whenever there is a set of alternatives Pareto-dominating some other alternatives, any decision rule selecting this set of Pareto-dominating alternatives is optimal in the sense of maximizing the probability of avoiding the selection of worst maximax alternatives. Clearly, plurality alternatives tend to be Pareto-dominating, and hence plurality voting is the most obvious candidate to be the optimal decision rule in terms of the γMX-index. We write Ml > Mh whenever mli > m h i for every i. That is, every individ- ual i ranks alternative l higher than alternative h. This is equivalent to Pareto- dominance. Then, consider the following set P(M) = {l ∈ K such that there exists h ∈ K with Ml > Mh}. Proposition 4.6. For n×k societies and for any culture, whenever the set P(M) is non-empty, P(M) is the maximum γMX-optimal rule. 16 Finally, the simulations also generally select plurality as the best decision rule, across society sizes and cultures (see Appendix B for a discussion). 5. Maximin For the analysis of the maximin case we exploit a symmetry between maximin and maximax. This allows us to directly extrapolate results that we obtained from the maximax case to the maximin case. In particular, the results point to negative, the symmetric scoring rule of plurality, as the obvious candidate to be the optimal decision rule for maximin in terms of the three indices of consistency, α, β, and γ. Denote by 1 an n×k matrix with all entries equal to 1. Then, consider the follow- ing Theorem. Theorem 5.1. For n×k societies, symmetric cultures, every M ∈M, and l ∈ K: (1) αlMN (M) = 1 −α l MX((k + 1)1 −M), (2) βlMN (M) = 1 −γ l MX((k + 1)1 −M), and (3) γlMN (M) = 1 −β l MX((k + 1)1 −M). Theorem 5.1 allows the extrapolation of all analytical and simulations results ob- tained in the previous section for maximax that involve symmetric cultures to the case of maximin. This means that negative is the decision rule best suited to optimize maximin. For asymmetric cultures, Theorem 5.1 does not apply. To test the robust- ness of our theoretical findings when the culture is asymmetric, we estimate the value of the three indices for the case of the exponential distribution. Table 3 in Appen- dix B reports the results. Once more, it can be appreciated that negative generally emerges as the optimal scoring rule in the computational analysis (see Appendix B for a more detailed account of the results of the simulations). 6. Conclusions This paper explores the relation between ideals of justice and decision rules. Whereas ideals of justice are typically presented in cardinal terms, decision rules are primarily constructed on the basis of ordinal information. We study the cardinal consequences of using ordinal-based decision rules. We have shown that the optimal choice of decision rules depends on the criterion of justice that one wishes to follow. Among our specific findings we emphasize that our results identify a particularly prominent set of decision rules as optimal: the set of scoring rules. Moreover, the three most prominent scoring rules, plurality, Borda, and negative, are optimal for the three different ideals of justice. Maximax is best approached by plurality for any possible culture, maximin is best approached by negative, and, for a range of cultures, utilitarianism is best approached by Borda. 17 Moreover, in the latter case of utilitarianism we provide the mapping between cultures and optimal decision rules. Appendix A. Proofs Proof of Theorem 3.1. Recall that αlUT (M) = E[ ∑ i U l i n | M]. The independence of the random variables Uli across individuals allows us to write α l UT (M) = ∑ i E[U l i | Mi]/n. In addition, since, for every individual i, all the random variables are identi- cally distributed, we can write αlUT (M) = ∑ i E[U l i | Mli ]/n. Finally, since Ul1, . . . ,Uln are also identically distributed, we can write the last expression in terms of the num- ber of order statistics. First, note that, since U (h) i and U (h) j are identically distributed, we may simply write U(h). Then, αlUT (M) = ∑ h l (h)E[U(h)] n . The value of the difference between two alternatives l and q is αlUT (M)−α q UT (M) =∑ h l (h)E[U(h)] n − ∑ h q (h)E[U(h)] n = ∑ h(l (h)−q(h))E[U(h)] n . Note that ∑ h l (h) = ∑ h q (h) = n, and therefore ∑ h E[U (1)](l(h)−q(h)) n = 0. We then write αlUT (M)−α q UT (M) = ∑ h(l (h)−q(h))E[U(h)] n −∑ h E[U (1)](l(h)−q(h)) n and hence αlUT (M) − α q UT (M) = ∑ h(l (h)−q(h))(E[U(h)]−E[U(1)]) n . Note that E[U(k)] − E[U(1)] > 0. Then, multiplying and dividing by E[U(k)] − E[U(1)], we have αlUT (M) −α q UT (M) = E[U(k)] − E[U(1)] n ∑ h(l (h) − q(h))(E[U(h)] − E[U(1)]) E[U(k)] − E[U(1)] = E[U(k)] − E[U(1)] n ( ∑ h [l(h) − q(h)]S∗h). Since E[U(k)] − E[U(1)] > 0, it follows that, for every M, S∗ gives exactly the same ranking over the alternatives as the one given by utilitarianism. Hence, the two claims of the theorem follow. � Proof of Corollary 3.2. The first two points in the corollary follow directly from Theorem 3.1. To see the third claim, consider that a well known fact in order sta- tistics theory is that ∑ l E[U (l)] = kE[Uh] for any alternative h. Consequently, since the symmetry of the density function implies that E[Uh] = E[U(2)] = 1 2 , it follows immediately that E[U(l+1)] − E[U(l)] = c with 1 ≤ l ≤ 2. Then, from Theorem 3.1, Borda is the αUT -optimal decision rule. � Proof of Theorem 3.5. We report the proof for the uniform distribution. The cor- responding proof for any other parabolic function is analogous, and hence is omitted. We organize the proof by types of societies in ordinal terms. Type 1: Perfect correlation. This is the case when M1 = M2. Let, w.l.o.g., M1 = (3, 2, 1). Utilitarianism always selects alternative 1. Hence, βUT (M) = (1, 0, 0). 18 Type 2: Only best-correlation. Both individuals agree on the best alternative, but disagree on the others. Let, w.l.o.g., M1 = (3, 2, 1) and M2 = (3, 1, 2). Utilitarianism selects alternative 1, and then βUT (M) = (1, 0, 0). Type 3: Only worst-correlation. Both individuals coincide in the worst alternative, but disagree on the others. Let, w.l.o.g., M1 = (3, 2, 1) and M2 = (2, 3, 1). It is straightforward to see that βUT (M) = (1/2, 1/2, 0). Type 4: Only middle-correlation. Both individuals agree on the middle alternative, but disagree on the others.7 Let, w.l.o.g., M1 = (3, 2, 1) and M2 = (1, 2, 3). To compute the selection of utilitarianism we first need to derive the joint probability distribution associated to the continuous random variables U (1) i , U (2) i and U (3) i . The joint probability density function is f(u (1) i ,u (2) i ,u (3) i ) = { 6 if 1 ≥ u(3)i ≥ u (2) i ≥ u (1) i ≥ 0 0 otherwise. Hence, the density function for the two agents is f(u (1) i ,u (2) i ,u (3) i ,u (1) j ,u (2) j ,u (3) j ) =   36 if 1 ≥ u(3)i ≥ u (2) i ≥ u (1) i ≥ 0, and 1 ≥ u(3)j ≥ u (2) j ≥ u (1) j ≥ 0 0 otherwise. We can now calculate the probability of utilitarianism resulting in the selection of alternative 2. Alternative 2 will be the utilitarian winner whenever the sum of U (2) i and U (2) j is greater than U (1) i + U (3) j and U (3) i + U (1) j . Equivalently, (A.1)∫ R ∫ R ∫ R ∫ R ∫ Ha ∫ Hb f(u (1) i ,u (2) i ,u (3) i ,u (1) j ,u (2) j ,u (3) j )du (3) i du (3) j du (2) i du (2) j du (1) i du (1) j , where Ha and Hb are the sets Ha = {t : t ≤ u (2) i + u (2) j − u (1) i } and Hb = {t : t ≤ u (2) i + u (2) j −u (1) j }. Then, (A.1) can be expressed as (A.2)∫ 1 0 ∫ 1 0 ∫ 1 u (1) j ∫ 1 u (1) i ∫ min{1,u(2)i +u(2)j −u(1)i } u (2) j ∫ min{1,u(2)i +u(2)j −u(1)j } u (2) i 36du (3) i du (3) j du (2) i du (2) j du (1) i du (1) j . It can be shown that the above is .3 (for any parabolic distribution, the value of the integral is strictly lower than 1/3). Clearly, the utilitarian choice is, with equal probability, either alternative 1 or 3. Then, βUT (M) = (.35, .3, .35) (for the remaining parabolic functions, β1UT (M) = β 3 UT (M) > β 2 UT (M). 7This type of societies has attracted a good deal of attention. Interestingly, Börgers and Postl (2007) study whether for this class of societies there are incentive-compatible rules which elicit utilities and implement efficient decisions. 19 Type 5. No correlation. Individuals do not agree on the ranking of any alternative. Let, w.l.o.g., M1 = (3, 2, 1) and M1 = (2, 1, 3). Hence, alternative 1 dominates alternative 2, and consequently the utilitarian choice will never be alternative 2. We now show that alternative 1 has a higher probability of being the utilitarian choice than alternative 3. For any society where alternative 3 is better in utilitarian terms, a society can be injectively constructed such that: (i) it is of type 5, and (ii) the utilitarian choice is alternative 1. Simply write u ′1 1 = u 3 2, u ′2 1 = u 1 2, u ′3 1 = u 2 2, u ′1 2 = u 2 1, u ′2 2 = u 3 1, and u ′3 2 = u 1 1. 8 Clearly, the constructed society is of type 5, and to see that the utilitarian choice is alternative 1, notice that u ′1 1 + u ′1 2 = u 3 2 + u 2 1 > u 3 2 + u 3 1 > u11 + u 1 2 > u 1 1 + u 2 2 = u ′3 2 + u ′3 1 . Then, β 1 UT (M) > β 3 UT (M) > β 2 UT (M) = 0. Taking into consideration all five cases together, implosion is the βUT -optimal gen- erator. This proves the first part of the theorem. The second part follows immediately from the above analysis.� Proof of Theorem 4.1. First note that only alternatives ranked best by some agents can provide the highest maximax value. In fact, due to the i.i.d. nature of utility realizations across individuals, for all M ∈M and for all h,l ∈ K βlMX(M) ≥ β h MX(M) ⇔ l (k) ≥ h(k). It is immediate that every decision rule f in δ(SPl) is a βMX-optimal decision rule since it selects precisely that subset of the alternatives that are ranked best by the largest number of individuals. Furthermore, for every f 6∈ δ(SPl) there exists an M ∈ M and an alternative h ∈ K such that h ∈ f(M) \ SPl(M). Consequently, there is an l ∈ K such that l(k) > h(k) and hence f is not a βMX-optimal decision rule.� Proof of Corollary 4.2. We prove the corollary by showing that, for any given K, when n tends to infinity, plurality is the only scoring rule in δ(SPl). Take a scoring rule f different from plurality. We now find a real number nf such that for every positive integer n with n > nf , there exists a profile M ∈M with f(M) 6⊆ SPl(M). Given that f is not plurality, Sk−1 > 0. Take nf = 2( 1 Sk−1 − 1), and n > nf . If n is odd, consider the following matrix M: Mi = (k,k − 1,k − 2, . . . , 2, 1) for all 1 ≤ i ≤ n+1 2 , and Mj = (1,k,k − 1, . . . , 3, 2) for all n+32 ≤ j ≤ n. Plurality selects alternative 1. Scoring rule f assigns to alternative 1 a total score of n+1 2 , while the total score of alternative 2 is n−1 2 + n+1 2 Sk−1. We now show that n−1 2 + n+1 2 Sk−1 > n+1 2 , or equivalently n+1 2 Sk−1 > 1. Our original assumption that n > nf = 2( 1 Sk−1 − 1) guarantees the latter inequality. If n is even, consider the matrix M with Mi = (k,k − 1,k − 2, . . . , 2, 1) for all 1 ≤ i ≤ n 2 , and Mj = (1,k,k − 1, . . . , 3, 2) for all n+22 ≤ j ≤ n − 1 and Mn = 8Note, that under i.i.d., this argument is distribution free. 20 (1,k − 1,k − 2, . . . , 2,k) . An argument analogous to the one above shows that plurality selects alternative 1 while f selects alternative 2. Then, we have shown that, for n > nf , decision rule f is not a βMX-optimal scoring rule, which proves the result.� Proof of Lemma 4.3. The distribution function of a uniform k order statistic is F (k)(t) = tk and of a (k−1) order statistic is F (k−1)(t) = tk+ktk−1(1−t). Now, the dis- tribution function of Ul(n) when M l such that mli = k for every i ∈{1, . . . ,n}, is F(t) = tnk. Then, E[Ul(n) | M] = ∫ 1 0 t dF(t) dt dt = nk nk+1 . Analogously, E[Ul(n+1) | M ′] = (n+1)k (n+1)k+1 , where m ′l i = k for every i ∈ {1, . . . ,n,n + 1}. Finally, the distribution function of Ul(n+1) when M l with mli = k for every i ∈{1, . . . ,n,n + 1}\{j} and mlj = k − 1, is F(t) = tnk(tk+ktk−1(1−t)). Then, E[Ul(n+1) | M] = ∫ 1 0 t dF(t) dt dt = k(n2k+2nk+k−1) (nk+k)(nk+k+1) . Con- sequently, E[Ul(n+1)|M ′l] − E[Ul(n)|M l] = k (nk+1)(nk+k+1) and ∆ (k−1) n = E[Ul(n+1)|M l ] − E[Ul(n)|M l] = k(k−1) (nk+1)(nk+k)(nk+k+1) . Then, the result follows.� Proof of Proposition 4.4. We start by proving point (1). For every individual i, the distribution functions of her best, medium and worst random variables are F (3)(t) = t3, F (2)(t) = t3 + 3t2(1 − t), and F (1)(t) = 1 − (1 − t)3, respectively. The distribution function of the maximum of l(3), l(2) and n−l(3)−l(2) = l(1) best, medium and worst random variables is F(t) = (t3)l (3) (t3 + 3t2(1 − t))l (2) (1 − (1 − t)3)l (1) . The polynomial decomposition of the latter expression gives F(t) = l(2)∑ a=0 l(1)∑ b=0 3b∑ c=0 ( l(2) a )( l(1) b )( 3b c ) (−1)a+b+c3l (2)−a2at3l (3)+2l(2)+a+c. The density function is f(t) = l(2)∑ a=0 l(1)∑ b=0 3b∑ c=0 ( l(2) a )( l(1) b )( 3b c ) (−1)a+b+c3l (2)−a2a(3l(3)+2l(2)+a+c)t3l (3)+2l(2)+a+c−1. Finally, the expected value is E[Ul(n)|M] = l(2)∑ a=0 l(1)∑ b=0 3b∑ c=0 ( l(2) a )( l(1) b )( 3b c ) (−1)a+b+c3l (2)−a2a 3l(3) + 2l(2) + a + c 3l(3) + 2l(2) + a + c + 1 . We start the proof of part (2) of the theorem by stating the following lemma. Lemma A.1. Let {xa}a∈T∪{b}, b /∈ T 6= ∅ be a set of independent random variables. Then E[max{xa}a∈T∪{b}]−E[max{xa}a∈T ] ≤ E[max{xa}a∈S∪{b}]−E[max{xa}a∈S] for all S ⊆ T . 21 The lemma is straightforward, and hence we omit its proof. Since p ∈ SPl(M) it must be that p(3) ≥ h(3). Let h(3) < p(3) − 1. Vector (x,y,z) represents the case where x = p(3), y = p(2), and z = p(1). Then, it is immediate that E[Up (n) | M] ≥ E[(p(3), 0, 0)].9 Since h(3) < p(3)−1 it is immediate that E[Uh(n) | M] ≤ E[(p (3)−2,n− p(3) + 2, 0)]. By Lemma A.1 E[(p(3) − 2,n− p(3) + 2, 0)] ≤ E[(p(3) − 2, 0, 0)] + (n− p(3) + 2)∆ (2) p(3)−2. We now prove that E[(p (3), 0, 0)] > E[(p(3) − 2,n− p(3) + 2, 0)]. By showing the latter, we are excluding the possibility of h being an optimal alternative whenever h(3) < p(3) − 1. Let us assume by way of contradiction that E[(p(3), 0, 0)] ≤ E[(p(3) − 2,n− p(3) + 2, 0)]. Note E[(p(3), 0, 0)] = E[(p(3)−2, 0, 0)] + ∆(3) p(3)−2 + ∆ (3) p(3)−1. Then it must be that ∆ (3) p(3)−2 + ∆ (3) p(3)−1 ≤ (n− p (3) + 2)∆ (2) p(3)−2. The latter leads to n ≥ (3p(3)−3)(3p(3)−2) (3p(3)+1) + p(3) − 2. Now, since p is a plurality alternative, n ≤ 3p(3) − 2. Then it must be that 3p(3)−2 ≥ (3p (3)−3)(3p(3)−2) (3p(3)+1) +p(3)−2. This can only be the case if p(3) ≤ 5. For all 2 ≤ p(3) ≤ 5, and for all p(3) ≤ n ≤ 3p(3)−2 the direct evaluation of the expression in point (1) of the proposition shows that E[(p(3), 0, 0)] > E[(p(3) −2,n−p(3) + 2, 0)], hence, a contradiction arises, and then it must be that E[(p(3), 0, 0)] > E[(p(3)−2,n−p(3)+2, 0)] for all n and all p defined as in the proposition, as desired. The latter shows that it can only be either h(3) = p(3) or h(3) = p(3) − 1. In the first case it is immediate that, for h to be an optimal alternative, then it can only be that h(2) ≥ p(2). For the second case, note that E[Uh(n) | M] = E[(p (3) − 1, h(2),n−p(3) + 1−h(2))]. Now, by Lemma A.1 E[(p(3)−1, h(2),n−p(3) + 1−h(2))] ≤ E[(p(3)−1, 0, 0)]+h(2)∆(2) p(3)−1 +(n−p (3) +1−h(2))∆(1) p(3)−1. Now, since p is the plurality alternative, it must be that n ≤ 3p(3)−1. Hence, (n−p(3) +1−h(2)) ≤ 2p(3)−h(2). For all p(3) ≥ 1, 2p(3)−h(2) ≤ 3p(3)−1. It can be checked that ∆ (2) p(3)−1 ∆ (1) p(3)−1 = 3p(3)−1. Hence, (n− p(3) + 1 − h(2))∆(1) p(3)−1 ≤ ∆ (2) p(3)−1. Then, E[(p (3) − 1, h(2),n− p(3) + 1 − h(2))] ≤ E[(p(3) −1, 0, 0)] + (h(2) + 1)∆(2) p(3)−1. For alternative p, E[U p (n) | M] ≥ E[(p(3), 0, 0)] = E[(p(3)−1, 0, 0)] + ∆(3) p(3)−1. Hence, for alternative h to be an αMX-optimal alternative, it must be that (h(2) + 1)∆ (2) p(3)−1 ≥ ∆ (3) p(3)−1. The latter implies that h (2) ≥ 3p (3) 2 − 1 and hence h(2) ≥ n−1 2 , as desired.� Proof of Proposition 4.6. We start by noticing that, for every l ∈ P(M), index γlMX = 1. This follows trivially from the fact that, for every l ∈ P(M), there is an h ∈ K (possibly a different h for every l) such that Ml > Mh and hence Ul(n) > U h (n). We now show that for every l ∈ K \P(M), index γlMX < 1. Suppose, w.l.o.g. that l = 1. Since 1 6∈ P(M) for every h > 1 there is an agent ih such that m1ih < m h ih . 9Note that vector (p(3), 0, 0) may not be feasible in M. 22 Denote all these agents by I = ∪h∈K\{1}{ih}. P(U1(n) < U h (n) for all h > 1 | M) ≥ P(U1(n) = U 1 j for any j ∈ I | M) ·P(U2(n) = U 2 i2 | M) · . . . ·P(Uk(n) = U k ik | M). Clearly, the latter is strictly above 0, and the result follows.� Proof of Theorem 4.5. Take the structure of the proof of Theorem 3.5. Here, too, we provide the proof for the uniform distribution. The values of γMX(M) for any other parabolic function are exactly the ones provided below. Then, the values of γMX(M) for the different types of societies are: Type 1: It is straightforward that γMX(M) = (1, 1, 0). Type 2: It is straightforward that γMX(M) = (1, 1/2, 1/2). Type 3: It is straightforward that γMX(M) = (1, 1, 0). Type 4: It is easy to appreciate that alternative 2 can never be the maximax alternative, and hence γMX(M) = (1, 0, 1). Type 5: It is straightforward that 1 = γ1MX(M) > γ 3 MX(M) > γ 2 MX(M). Finally, taking into consideration all five cases together, explosion is an optimal decision rule. The second part of the Theorem follows trivially from the above anal- ysis. � Proof of Theorem 5.1. (1) Recall that we denote the distribution function of the l-th order statistic by F (l)(t). First note that P(Ul(1) ≤ t|M) = 1 − P(U l (1) > t|M) = 1 − (1 −F (k)(t))l(k) · . . . · (1 −F (1)(t))l(1) . Given the symmetry of the culture, it follows that, for every l ∈ K, F (l)(t) = 1 − F (k−l+1)(1 − t). Therefore, P(Ul(1) ≤ t|M) = 1 −F (1)(1 − t)l(k) · . . . ·F (k)(1 − t)l(1) . The latter expression is 1 −P(Ul(n) ≤ t|(k + 1)1 − M). It follows that E[Ul(1) | M] = E[U l (n) | (k + 1)1 − M], and hence αlMN (M) = 1 −α l MX((k + 1)1 −M). (2) Given M, βlMN (M) is the probability that alternative l is the best maximin alternative. That is, βlMN (M) = P(U l (1) > U h (1) for all h ∈ K \ {l} | M). Equiv- alently, βlMN (M) = 1 − P(There exists h ∈ K \ {l} such that U l (1) < U h (1) | M). For every symmetric culture we then have that βlMN (M) = 1 − P(There exists h ∈ K \{l} such that Ul(n) > U h (n) | (k + 1)1 −M). The latter expression is equivalent to 1 −γlMX((k + 1)1 −M). (3) Given M, γlMN (M) is the probability that alternative l is not the worst max- imin alternative. That is, γlMN (M) = 1 − P(U l (1) < U h (1) for all h ∈ K \ {l} | M). Equivalently, γlMN (M) = P(There exists h ∈ K \ {l} such that U l (1) > U h (1) | M). For every symmetric culture we then have that γlMN (M) = P(There exists h ∈ K \ {l} such that Ul(n) < U h (n) | (k + 1)1 − M). The latter expression is equiva- lent to 1−P(Ul(n) > U h (n) for all h ∈ K\{l} | (k+1)1−M) = 1−β l MX((k+1)1−M).� 23 Appendix B. Computational Analysis10 In this section we provide the technical details of the computational analysis, and report some further results. We study societies of size n×k, with n×k ∈{2, 3, 5, 10, 100}×{3, 4, 5, 7}, and three different cultures. First, we consider societies where the utility values of the individu- als are drawn independently from a uniform distribution on the interval [0, 1]. Second, we consider the standard normal distribution in the interval (−∞,∞). Finally, to study societies with cultures having asymmetric density functions, we study the case where the utility values are drawn independently from an exponential distribution with λ = 1. For every single size of society and culture, we independently draw 3, 841, 600 car- dinal societies. Then, for every combination of size of society and culture, we check the performance of a set of scoring rules across all the 3, 841, 600 simulated cardinal societies. The set of scoring rules is defined as follows. We randomly generate 47 scoring rules by independently drawing values from a uniform distribution on the in- terval [0, 1]. Apart from this 47 randomly-generated scoring rules, our analysis always includes the three most prominent ones: plurality, Borda, and negative. Finally, for the case of the analysis of utilitarianism, we also include the optimal scoring rules as predicted in Theorem 3.1. Since the β and γ indices measure probabilities of success, we use interval estimation methods for binomial distributions. Our sample size provides a confidence interval of length .001 around the value of the corresponding index,11 assuming that the variance of the value of the index is the highest possible for a binomial distribution (i.e., .25). This is a conservative method to compare significant differences across scoring rules.12 For the α−index, we estimate both the value of the index and its variance in order to construct confidence intervals that depend on the estimated variance.13 The simulations complement the theoretical results obtained in the text by studying the following cases: • Utilitarianism: βUT for the uniform, normal and exponential distributions, and γUT for the exponential distribution. 10We are grateful to the Advanced Computing Center for Research and Education at Vanderbilt University for providing the necessary computing resources. 11To determine that the difference between two values is significantly different than zero, this method provides a confidence interval of length .001 × 21/2 for such difference. 12The use of this method might provide unnecessarily wide intervals; however, it allows us to find significant differences across scoring rules without having to estimate their covariance. 13Given our sample size, with the exponential distribution and the normal distribution the length of these intervals varies between .002 and .004 for the case of maximax and between .0002 and .002 for the case of maximin. With the uniform distribution, the length of the interval varies between .00001 and .0005. Note that the differences across distributions are due to their different ranges. 24 • Maximax: αMX for the uniform (with k > 3), normal and exponential distri- butions, and γMX for the exponential distribution. • Maximin: βMN for the uniform, normal and exponential distributions, αMN for the exponential distribution, and γMN for the exponential distribution. Table 1 reports the βUT and γUT values of the optimal scoring rules according to Theorem 3.1. Moreover, for the sake of comparison, the table also includes the βUT and γUT -values that the three most prominent scoring rules, plurality, Borda and neg- ative, attain in the simulations. Accordingly, Tables 2 and 3 report the corresponding values attained by plurality, Borda and negative. As shown in Tables 1, 2 and 3, for each of the three ideals of justice, each probability distributions, and each performance index, the scoring rule that provides the highest value is generally the one predicted in the theoretical results presented in the text. This means that the scoring rule determined by Theorem 3.1 is the best in the case of utilitarianism, plurality is the best in the case of maximax, and negative is the best in the case of maximin, across probability distributions. There are only some exceptions for small society sizes, in which the frequency of ties in the number of points sometimes causes distortions. More specifically, for utilitarianism the scoring rule predicted in Theorem 3.1 pro- vides a higher value than not only plurality and negative (and Borda, when Borda is not the S∗) but also than the best randomly-generated scoring rule. In addition, we find that S∗ cannot be rejected as the best-performing scoring rule.14 For maximax, plurality has a significantly higher expected value and a significantly higher probability of not selecting the worst alternative than Borda and negative, as predicted. There are only a few exceptions for small societies, wherein the frequency of ties causes distortions. In addition, the best randomly-generated scoring rule is in a neighborhood of plurality. Moreover, as the size of the society increases (i.e., as the probability of ties decreases) the values of plurality and of the best randomly- generated scoring rule converge. In particular, for societies of 100 individuals we find that plurality is significantly better than the best randomly-generated scoring rule. For maximin, when the number of individuals is larger than the number of alter- natives, the results are analogous to the case of maximax. That is, negative has a significantly higher expected value, a significantly higher probability of selecting the best alternative, and a significantly higher probability of not selecting the worst alter- native than Borda and plurality. Furthermore, the best randomly-generated scoring rule is in a neighborhood around negative. In contrast, notice that for societies with n below or around k, it is likely than more that one alternative is not the worst for any of the individuals. In such cases, negative chooses randomly between these alternatives, which is not necessarily optimal and is the cause of some distortions. As the size of 14We find a few exceptions in small societies due to the frequency of ties. 25 the society increases, this effect vanishes. In particular, for societies of 100 individuals we find that negative is significantly better than the best randomly-generated scoring rule. 26 T a b l e 1 . U ti li ta ri a n is m : V a lu es o f th e β U T a n d γ U T o b ta in ed fr o m th e si m u la ti o n s a n a ly si s† β U T : γ U T : u n if o rm n o rm a l e x p o n e n ti a l e x p o n e n ti a l S o c ie ty S ∗ S P l S B d S N g S ∗ S P l S B d S N g S ∗ S P l S B d S N g S ∗ S P l S B d S N g 2 × 3 .7 4 2 0 4 .6 4 1 8 6 .7 3 9 2 8 .6 5 0 3 4 .7 3 4 1 6 .6 4 3 9 6 .7 3 4 1 6 .6 4 0 1 7 .7 1 3 1 3 .6 5 7 7 1 .6 9 4 5 0 .5 7 4 0 1 .9 5 3 8 2 .9 2 6 0 9 .9 4 4 4 9 .9 2 5 9 7 2 × 4 .7 4 2 0 9 .5 7 2 1 3 .7 4 2 0 9 .4 2 0 7 0 .7 3 5 6 2 .5 8 1 6 0 .7 2 6 9 1 .4 4 0 6 1 .6 9 1 5 3 .6 0 6 2 9 .6 5 9 9 0 .3 7 4 2 7 .9 8 9 2 8 .9 7 6 5 3 .9 8 9 6 0 .9 2 9 8 1 2 × 5 .7 4 7 6 1 .5 2 1 4 7 .7 4 7 6 1 .3 0 5 9 8 .7 3 5 5 2 .5 3 9 2 7 .7 2 0 6 5 .3 0 0 5 8 .6 7 6 3 7 .5 7 2 4 2 .6 3 4 7 3 .2 7 5 8 1 .9 9 7 8 3 .9 9 2 3 1 .9 9 8 3 2 .9 3 4 7 6 2 × 7 .7 6 0 5 3 .4 5 0 1 0 .7 6 0 5 3 .1 9 4 1 4 .7 3 2 4 3 .4 8 2 8 0 .7 1 2 7 8 .1 9 1 6 2 .6 5 9 0 2 .5 2 9 7 5 .6 0 1 2 2 .1 8 0 3 2 .9 9 9 8 1 .9 9 9 1 2 .9 9 9 9 7 .9 4 3 9 6 3 × 3 .7 7 3 7 1 .7 0 5 3 2 .7 7 3 7 1 .6 3 0 1 6 .7 6 6 8 4 .7 0 1 5 9 .7 6 6 8 4 .6 2 3 6 5 .7 2 9 6 9 .6 9 4 9 7 .7 2 0 3 7 .5 5 3 5 7 .9 4 8 6 1 .9 0 9 6 8 .9 4 9 7 8 .8 7 6 3 3 3 × 4 .7 5 3 3 2 .6 0 8 8 2 .7 5 3 3 2 .4 9 2 8 1 .7 4 5 1 8 .6 1 2 9 6 .7 4 1 9 9 .4 8 4 1 1 .6 9 0 1 6 .6 2 0 3 1 .6 7 1 1 2 .4 1 0 6 9 .9 8 7 0 5 .9 5 6 8 2 .9 8 6 9 3 .9 2 6 2 5 3 × 5 .7 4 7 9 8 .5 3 7 2 8 .7 4 7 9 8 .3 5 1 6 6 .7 3 6 5 0 .5 4 9 8 9 .7 3 0 2 6 .3 4 5 6 2 .6 6 8 9 6 .5 6 9 1 9 .6 3 7 6 1 .2 9 8 6 1 .9 9 6 5 8 .9 7 8 8 3 .9 9 6 6 6 .9 3 0 3 7 3 × 7 .7 5 0 3 1 .4 3 9 0 0 .7 5 0 3 1 .2 1 7 6 8 .7 2 9 5 3 .4 6 7 8 2 .7 1 8 0 5 .2 1 4 1 9 .6 4 4 4 3 .5 0 1 0 2 .5 9 0 1 8 .1 9 1 5 5 .9 9 9 6 8 .9 9 4 6 9 .9 9 9 7 6 .9 3 9 4 4 5 × 3 .7 6 1 1 9 .6 7 9 7 7 .7 6 1 1 9 .6 4 6 6 5 .7 4 9 8 8 .6 7 3 6 0 .7 4 9 8 8 .6 3 7 3 8 .6 9 9 3 4 .6 6 3 9 6 .6 9 0 1 4 .5 5 8 9 9 .9 3 7 7 1 .9 1 1 1 1 .9 3 6 8 2 .8 7 8 7 8 5 × 4 .7 4 5 5 5 .6 0 3 3 3 .7 4 5 5 5 .5 1 5 9 4 .7 3 2 4 4 .6 0 5 6 9 .7 2 9 1 2 .5 0 9 4 1 .6 6 6 8 6 .6 1 6 3 0 .6 4 4 2 0 .4 2 1 6 3 .9 8 2 2 3 .9 6 8 9 0 .9 8 1 7 0 .9 0 9 1 9 5 × 5 .7 4 1 8 6 .5 4 3 3 8 .7 4 1 8 6 .4 1 9 2 9 .7 2 5 3 9 .5 5 6 3 0 .7 1 9 7 7 .4 1 5 0 1 .6 4 8 2 1 .5 8 2 9 2 .6 1 3 6 1 .3 3 2 6 5 .9 9 4 6 1 .9 8 2 8 7 .9 9 4 4 5 .9 3 1 5 9 5 × 7 .7 4 5 2 3 .4 5 0 5 6 .7 4 5 2 3 .2 5 8 4 6 .7 2 0 1 8 .4 8 1 1 8 .7 1 0 7 0 .2 5 6 1 8 .6 2 6 7 8 .5 2 8 1 3 .5 7 1 0 2 .2 1 1 4 7 .9 9 9 4 5 .9 9 1 4 9 .9 9 9 4 7 .9 4 2 0 2 1 0 × 3 .7 5 8 3 6 .6 8 5 9 3 .7 5 8 3 6 .6 4 7 4 9 .7 4 4 1 6 .6 7 7 4 1 .7 4 4 1 6 .6 3 7 9 5 .6 8 7 7 3 .6 7 7 2 3 .6 6 5 2 1 .5 5 6 2 2 .9 3 1 2 3 .9 1 5 9 4 .9 2 8 6 0 .8 6 5 1 7 1 0 × 4 .7 4 4 5 1 .5 9 4 4 5 .7 4 4 5 1 .5 3 4 4 8 .7 2 7 4 2 .5 9 3 5 9 .7 2 4 8 0 .5 2 8 9 3 .6 5 4 3 4 .6 0 3 4 5 .6 3 2 7 0 .4 3 2 4 1 .9 7 9 0 3 .9 5 9 9 0 .9 7 7 1 9 .9 0 6 4 8 1 0 × 5 .7 4 0 4 2 .5 2 7 1 8 .7 4 0 4 2 .4 4 8 0 9 .7 1 8 7 7 .5 3 5 9 5 .7 1 4 7 1 .4 4 6 4 5 .6 3 5 6 7 .5 6 4 1 6 .6 0 2 6 8 .3 4 8 4 4 .9 9 3 3 0 .9 8 0 5 8 .9 9 2 1 3 .9 2 7 6 6 1 0 × 7 .7 4 2 7 6 .4 3 0 1 1 .7 4 2 7 6 .3 2 4 4 2 .7 1 5 1 2 .4 5 4 8 6 .7 0 7 4 6 .3 2 8 2 7 .6 1 6 7 2 .5 0 6 3 5 .5 6 2 7 9 .2 4 3 6 2 .9 9 9 2 5 .9 9 1 8 2 .9 9 9 0 0 .9 4 6 9 4 1 0 0 × 3 .7 5 8 5 1 .6 7 5 8 5 .7 5 8 5 1 .6 6 5 5 5 .7 4 1 2 9 .6 6 4 8 0 .7 4 1 2 9 .6 5 4 2 4 .6 8 0 8 4 .6 5 5 7 5 .6 7 1 9 0 .5 6 8 6 1 .9 2 3 5 6 .9 0 8 9 9 .9 1 9 7 5 .8 6 1 8 1 1 0 0 × 4 .7 4 4 4 6 .5 8 0 2 8 .7 4 4 4 6 .5 6 4 1 2 .7 2 2 5 0 .5 7 6 8 5 .7 2 1 4 9 .5 5 7 4 7 .6 4 8 1 5 .5 9 5 2 0 .6 2 7 6 0 .4 5 1 0 5 .9 7 4 5 4 .9 5 8 4 1 .9 7 0 5 6 .9 0 4 1 3 1 0 0 × 5 .7 3 9 4 9 .5 0 7 7 5 .7 3 9 4 9 .4 8 3 9 3 .7 1 4 2 2 .5 1 2 2 6 .7 1 1 7 4 .4 8 5 1 2 .6 3 1 7 6 .5 5 1 3 4 .6 0 0 4 4 .3 7 2 8 1 .9 9 1 1 3 .9 7 7 8 4 .9 8 8 3 5 .9 2 6 0 6 1 0 0 × 7 .7 4 1 7 0 .4 0 3 7 7 .7 4 1 7 0 .3 7 4 0 7 .7 1 0 8 2 .4 2 1 9 1 .7 0 4 8 7 .3 8 5 2 9 .6 1 7 6 3 .4 8 8 5 8 .5 6 5 5 8 .2 7 3 7 8 .9 9 8 8 3 .9 9 1 3 8 .9 9 7 8 0 .9 4 8 3 7 † S ∗ , S P l, S B d , S N g d en ot e th e op ti m al sc or in g ru le ac co rd in g to T h eo re m 3. 1, p lu ra li ty , B or d a, an d n eg at iv e, re sp ec ti ve ly . 27 T a b l e 2 . M a x im a x : V a lu es o f th e α M X a n d γ M X o b ta in ed fr o m th e si m u la ti o n s a n a ly si s† α M X : γ M X : u n if or m n or m al ex p on en ti al ex p on en ti al S oc ie ty S P l S B d S N g S P l S B d S N g S P l S B d S N g S P l S B d S N g 2 × 3 .7 99 97 .8 04 71 .7 64 20 1. 02 88 3 1. 01 67 5 .8 88 00 2. 08 28 5 2. 06 07 7 1. 87 43 6 .9 33 46 .9 44 51 .9 00 28 2 × 4 .8 33 37 .8 26 40 .7 43 31 1. 16 31 4 1. 12 77 7 .8 13 35 2. 28 31 1 2. 22 06 4 1. 77 46 5 .9 82 07 .9 89 53 .9 07 19 2 × 5 .8 57 18 .8 45 81 .7 29 62 1. 26 77 1 1. 20 77 0 .7 67 62 2. 44 95 9 2. 34 40 9 1. 71 64 1 .9 95 24 .9 98 32 .9 15 28 2 × 7 .8 88 89 .8 71 09 .7 12 71 1. 42 39 7 1. 32 05 4 .7 12 14 2. 71 86 4 2. 52 74 0 1. 65 12 7 .9 99 67 .9 99 97 .9 29 34 3 × 3 .8 50 06 .8 51 54 .8 14 45 1. 23 54 7 1. 23 68 4 1. 07 89 3 2. 39 92 0 2. 39 54 1 2. 14 75 9 .8 98 32 .9 15 57 .8 33 22 3 × 4 .8 69 58 .8 69 81 .8 09 95 1. 32 76 9 1. 31 99 6 1. 05 85 9 2. 55 33 2 2. 53 05 4 2. 11 49 5 .9 58 10 .9 69 97 .8 80 68 3 × 5 .8 84 37 .8 82 01 .7 98 62 1. 40 35 2 1. 37 86 9 1. 01 63 1 2. 68 50 1 2. 63 06 2 2. 05 35 9 .9 82 76 .9 88 74 .8 93 27 3 × 7 .9 05 83 .8 97 56 .7 85 28 1. 52 32 9 1. 45 87 7 .9 67 13 2. 90 20 5 2. 77 20 5 1. 98 59 2 .9 97 17 .9 98 21 .9 13 74 5 × 3 .8 94 72 .8 93 55 .8 72 89 1. 45 26 6 1. 44 32 0 1. 33 51 2 2. 76 75 5 2. 74 86 9 2. 55 78 2 .8 67 73 .8 68 21 .7 98 03 5 × 4 .9 10 48 .9 04 89 .8 68 42 1. 54 35 2 1. 50 62 9 1. 31 33 3 2. 93 55 6 2. 86 20 7 2. 52 19 2 .9 47 76 .9 39 03 .8 46 10 5 × 5 .9 20 99 .9 12 65 .8 65 32 1. 61 22 1 1. 55 16 2 1. 29 96 8 3. 06 74 3 2. 94 60 1 2. 49 86 1 .9 75 17 .9 69 49 .8 76 60 5 × 7 .9 34 00 .9 22 58 .8 57 10 1. 71 00 6 1. 61 47 0 1. 26 21 4 3. 26 58 9 3. 06 76 7 2. 43 87 9 .9 92 41 .9 91 18 .9 04 23 10 × 3 .9 38 16 .9 36 26 .9 26 09 1. 73 67 7 1. 72 05 6 1. 64 56 7 3. 31 84 7 3. 28 41 2 3. 13 25 5 .8 27 51 .8 16 54 .7 56 54 10 × 4 .9 45 17 .9 41 70 .9 24 62 1. 79 63 3 1. 76 39 5 1. 63 58 7 3. 44 23 7 3. 37 26 4 3. 11 43 5 .9 10 72 .8 97 93 .8 19 53 10 × 5 .9 50 76 .9 45 35 .9 23 26 1. 84 74 3 1. 79 45 0 1. 62 76 7 3. 55 18 1 3. 43 59 7 3. 09 80 3 .9 53 22 .9 38 46 .8 55 79 10 × 7 .9 58 21 .9 50 25 .9 21 27 1. 92 51 7 1. 83 80 6 1. 61 48 6 3. 72 42 2 3. 52 89 1 3. 07 48 5 .9 84 58 .9 74 15 .8 95 93 10 0 × 3 .9 91 43 .9 91 28 .9 90 80 2. 55 78 4 2. 55 16 2 2. 53 31 1 5. 32 86 4 5. 31 10 7 5. 25 78 2 .7 24 74 .7 17 85 .6 96 00 10 0 × 4 .9 91 89 .9 91 56 .9 90 74 2. 57 70 3 2. 56 31 9 2. 53 11 3 5. 38 29 5 5. 34 40 3 5. 25 49 5 .8 17 29 .8 04 22 .7 73 60 10 0 × 5 .9 92 28 .9 91 76 .9 90 71 2. 59 36 2 2. 57 11 2 2. 52 97 8 5. 43 00 6 5. 36 73 1 5. 25 03 0 .8 71 28 .8 54 21 .8 19 56 10 0 × 7 .9 92 88 .9 92 02 .9 90 63 2. 62 15 6 2. 58 31 9 2. 52 79 7 5. 51 00 8 5. 39 86 4 5. 24 39 2 .9 29 83 .9 08 51 .8 71 64 † S P l, S B d , S N g d en ot e p lu ra li ty , B or d a, an d n eg at iv e, re sp ec ti ve ly . 28 T a b l e 3 . M a x im in : V a lu es o f th e α M N , β M N a n d γ M N o b ta in ed fr o m th e si m u la ti o n s a n a ly si s† α M N : β M N : γ M N : e x p o n e n ti a l u n if o rm n o rm a l e x p o n e n ti a l e x p o n e n ti a l S o c ie ty S P l S B d S N g S P l S B d S N g S P l S B d S N g S P l S B d S N g S P l S B d S N g 2 × 3 .7 4 9 8 0 .8 2 7 5 8 .7 9 1 5 2 .6 1 6 9 5 7 3 9 4 6 .7 0 0 3 8 .6 1 6 9 7 .7 3 8 8 6 .6 9 9 6 3 .6 1 6 8 8 .7 3 9 3 4 .7 0 0 0 4 .8 3 3 3 3 .9 4 4 6 3 1 2 × 4 .7 9 9 7 9 .9 5 2 1 8 .7 2 4 6 2 .5 3 2 4 4 .7 3 3 9 6 .4 4 0 4 7 .5 3 2 2 5 .7 3 4 0 0 .4 4 0 6 1 .5 3 1 9 7 .7 3 4 0 7 .4 4 0 4 7 .8 7 4 6 9 .9 8 9 4 8 1 2 × 5 .8 3 3 0 9 1 .0 5 2 6 1 .6 8 3 3 0 .4 7 3 2 1 .7 3 2 0 0 .3 1 3 8 7 .4 7 3 2 2 .7 3 1 7 2 .3 1 3 6 3 .4 7 2 7 2 .7 3 1 7 8 .3 1 2 9 4 .8 9 9 9 1 .9 9 8 3 7 1 2 × 7 .8 7 5 1 8 1 .2 0 9 7 0 .6 3 3 7 5 .3 9 4 6 7 .7 3 1 5 1 .1 9 5 2 6 .3 9 4 4 8 .7 3 1 4 8 .1 9 5 0 3 .3 9 4 7 6 .7 3 1 6 5 .1 9 5 5 2 .9 2 8 6 0 .9 9 9 9 7 1 3 × 3 .4 9 0 4 7 .5 2 8 5 6 .5 2 2 7 0 .5 7 9 2 3 .6 6 6 6 3 .6 6 5 8 1 .5 7 9 2 9 .6 6 6 3 3 .6 6 5 3 0 .5 7 8 8 3 .6 6 5 8 4 .6 6 4 9 4 .8 1 4 5 7 .8 8 3 9 7 .9 2 5 7 7 3 × 4 .5 0 7 5 6 .5 9 7 9 6 .5 3 9 9 2 .4 7 2 8 5 .6 4 0 1 7 .5 4 5 8 4 .4 7 3 1 5 .6 3 9 9 4 .5 4 5 7 7 .4 7 2 9 7 .6 4 0 1 9 .5 4 5 8 9 .8 5 4 2 0 .9 4 1 5 4 1 3 × 5 .5 1 5 5 2 .6 5 8 2 7 .5 0 3 9 3 .4 0 1 7 8 .6 3 0 2 2 .3 8 2 0 1 .4 0 1 1 3 .6 2 9 9 7 .3 8 1 6 5 .4 0 1 6 4 .6 3 0 2 2 .3 8 1 7 5 .8 8 0 0 4 .9 6 8 2 5 1 3 × 7 .5 2 0 4 8 .7 5 6 4 6 .4 5 9 7 8 .3 1 1 9 7 .6 2 3 7 2 .2 2 7 3 5 .3 1 2 1 1 .6 2 3 8 5 .2 2 7 1 8 .3 1 1 9 3 .6 2 3 6 8 .2 2 7 5 3 .9 1 1 5 3 .9 8 9 0 5 1 5 × 3 .2 7 2 0 5 .2 9 8 7 2 .3 0 3 1 2 .5 0 2 4 3 .5 8 7 5 3 .6 0 9 9 0 .5 0 2 4 9 .5 8 8 3 1 .6 1 0 3 1 .5 0 2 6 9 .5 8 8 1 5 .6 1 0 2 9 .7 7 7 5 0 .8 4 1 5 3 .8 7 6 6 3 5 × 4 .2 7 8 7 2 .3 3 3 4 1 .3 3 4 4 0 .4 0 3 8 2 .5 4 8 0 2 .5 6 2 9 6 .4 0 3 7 5 .5 4 7 7 4 .5 6 2 7 6 .4 0 3 7 4 .5 4 7 4 9 .5 6 2 5 5 .8 3 1 6 4 .9 0 6 3 7 .9 5 3 3 2 5 × 5 .2 8 1 7 2 .3 6 3 1 3 .3 4 4 5 2 .3 3 8 8 3 .5 2 5 7 5 .4 8 8 7 3 .3 3 9 4 1 .5 2 6 0 0 .4 8 8 2 9 .3 3 8 7 6 .5 2 5 6 9 .4 8 8 4 4 .8 6 4 1 9 .9 3 8 4 7 .9 9 2 2 9 5 × 7 .2 8 1 8 8 .4 1 0 8 0 .3 1 5 1 9 .2 5 8 3 1 .5 0 2 8 9 .2 9 7 6 5 .2 5 8 0 0 .5 0 2 9 4 .2 9 7 9 1 .2 5 8 4 5 .5 0 2 9 8 .2 9 7 7 0 .9 0 0 8 5 .9 6 7 6 9 1 1 0 × 3 .1 2 5 8 3 .1 3 7 8 1 .1 4 1 0 0 .4 4 5 9 7 .5 1 0 9 2 .5 3 2 9 6 .4 4 6 3 6 .5 1 1 1 2 .5 3 3 1 0 .4 4 5 9 2 .5 1 1 1 2 .5 3 3 0 8 .7 4 5 9 6 .7 9 3 6 1 .8 1 4 5 4 1 0 × 4 .1 2 6 2 3 .1 5 0 5 8 .1 5 7 8 8 .3 4 6 4 1 .4 5 5 5 0 .4 9 8 7 5 .3 4 6 5 7 .4 5 5 5 4 .4 9 8 6 8 .3 4 6 6 2 .4 5 5 1 4 .4 9 8 2 3 .8 0 6 4 3 .8 6 5 2 2 .9 0 0 1 2 1 0 × 5 .1 2 5 9 3 .1 6 0 9 4 .1 7 1 7 3 .2 8 4 7 4 .4 2 1 8 9 .4 7 6 9 4 .2 8 4 9 9 .4 2 2 2 9 .4 7 6 8 0 .2 8 4 7 4 .4 2 1 7 4 .4 7 6 5 9 .8 4 4 0 4 .9 0 3 3 2 .9 4 6 5 4 1 0 × 7 .1 2 5 1 5 .1 7 7 9 6 .1 8 6 7 1 .2 1 1 1 4 .3 8 3 2 3 .4 1 7 0 7 .2 1 0 7 1 .3 8 3 0 3 .4 1 7 5 8 .2 1 1 1 0 .3 8 3 4 2 .4 1 6 4 6 .8 8 6 7 3 .9 4 1 4 2 .9 8 9 6 2 1 0 0 × 3 .0 1 0 7 6 .0 1 1 2 9 .0 1 1 4 8 .3 6 4 8 2 .3 8 7 6 8 .3 9 6 2 3 .3 6 4 7 9 .3 8 7 2 2 .3 9 6 1 4 .3 6 5 8 0 .3 8 8 2 6 .3 9 6 8 8 .6 9 1 1 3 .7 0 8 3 4 .7 1 4 9 9 1 0 0 × 4 .0 1 0 7 3 .0 1 1 6 6 .0 1 2 1 6 .2 7 6 3 5 .3 1 0 9 2 .3 2 9 6 8 .2 7 5 8 7 .3 1 0 1 4 .3 2 9 3 1 .2 7 6 1 9 .3 1 0 1 5 .3 2 9 4 1 .7 6 7 5 9 .7 8 8 6 9 .8 0 0 1 6 1 0 0 × 5 .0 1 0 7 1 .0 1 1 9 5 .0 1 2 7 8 .2 2 2 1 3 .2 6 3 0 7 .2 9 2 2 1 .2 2 2 3 1 .2 6 3 3 5 .2 9 2 3 2 .2 2 2 7 4 .2 6 3 3 2 .2 9 2 3 1 .8 1 3 2 1 .8 3 5 6 7 .8 5 0 6 5 1 0 0 × 7 .0 1 0 6 4 .0 1 2 3 7 .0 1 3 9 9 .1 6 0 0 4 .2 0 7 6 6 .2 5 5 0 7 .1 6 0 2 9 .2 0 7 9 0 .2 5 5 7 7 .1 5 9 9 3 .2 0 7 7 5 .2 5 5 4 3 .8 6 6 0 5 .8 8 7 1 7 .9 0 5 9 2 † S P l, S B d , S N g d en ot e p lu ra li ty , B or d a, an d n eg at iv e, re sp ec ti ve ly . 29 References [1] Balakrishnan, N. and K.S. Sultan (1998), “Recurrence Relations and Identities for Moments of Order Statistics,” in N. Balakrishnan and C.R. Rao (eds.) Handbook of Statistics 16, North- Holland. [2] Barbera, S. and M. Jackson (2004), “Choosing How to Choose: Self-Stable Majority Rules and Constitutions,” Quarterly Journal of Economics, 119:1011-1048. [3] Barbera, S. and M. Jackson (2006), “On the Weights of Nations: Assigning Voting Weights in a Heterogeneous Union,” Journal of Political Economy, 114:317-339. [4] Barnett, V.D. (1966), “Order Statistics Estimators of the Location of the Cauchy Distribution,” Journal of the American Statistical Association, 61:1205-1218. [5] Benoit, J.P. and L.A. Kornhauser (2007), “Only a Dictatorship is Efficient or Neutral,” mimeo, LBS. [6] Börgers, T. and P. Postl (2007), “Efficient Compromising,” mimeo, University of Michigan. [7] Black, D. (1958), The Theory of Committees and Elections. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [8] Brams, S.J. and P.C. Fishburn (1978), “Approval Voting,” American Political Science Review, 72:831-847. [9] Bordley, R.F. (1983), “A Pragmatic Method for Evaluating Election Schemes through Simula- tion,” American Political Science Review, 77:123-141. [10] Caplin, A. and B. Nalebuff (1988), “On 64%-Majority Rule,” Econometrica, 56:787-814. [11] Dasgupta, P and E. Maskin (2008), “On the Robustness of Majority Rule,” Journal of the European Economic Association, forthcoming. [12] DeMeyer, F. and C.R. Plott (1970), “The Probability of a Cyclical Majority,” Econometrica, 38:345-354. [13] Gehrlein, W.V. (1997), “Condorcet’s Paradox and the Condorcet Efficiency of Voting Rules,” Mathematica Japonica, 45: 173-199. [14] Kamps, U. (1991), “A General Recurrence Relation for Moments of Order Statistics in a Class of Probability Distributions and Characterizations,” Metrika, 38:215-225. [15] Kamps, U. (1992), “Identities for the Difference of Moments of Successive Order Statistics and Record Values,” Metron, 50:179-187. [16] Levin, J. and B. Nalebuff (1995), “An Introduction to Vote-Counting Schemes,” Journal of Economic Perspectives, 9:3-26. [17] Maggi, G. and M. Morelli (2006), “Self-Enforcing Voting in International Organizations,” Amer- ican Economic Review, Vol. 96-4:1137-58. [18] Merrill, S. (1984), “A Comparison of Efficiency of Multicandidate Electoral Systems,” American Journal of Political Science, 28:23-48. [19] Myerson, R. (2002),“Comparison of Scoring Rules in Poisson Voting Games,” Journal of Eco- nomic Theory, 103:219-251. [20] Nurmi, H. (1983), “Voting Procedures: A Summary Analysis,” British Journal of Political Science, 13:181-208. [21] Rae, D. (1969), “Decision Rules and Individual Values in Constitutional Choice,” American Political Science Review, 63:40-56. [22] Saari, D.G. (1999), “Explaining All Three-Alternative Voting Outcomes,” Journal of Economic Theory, 87:313-355. 30 [23] Teichroew, D. (1956), “Tables of Expected Values of Order Statistics and Products of Or- der Statistics for Samples of Size Twenty and Less from the Normal Distribution,” Annals of Mathematical Statistics, 27:410-426. [24] Weber, R.J, (1978), “Comparison of Voting Systems,” mimeo, Cowles Foundation. work_lsyeyzdbr5hk5ook2zv4e24f6y ---- WPS 8-2014 Politicising Europe's Justice Deficit - Wilkinson - Final This paper can be downloaded without charge from LSE Law, Society and Economy Working Papers at: www.lse.ac.uk/collections/law/wps/wps.htm and the Social Sciences Research Network electronic library at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2379043. © Michael A. Wilkinson. Users may download and/or print one copy to facilitate their private study or for non-commercial research. Users may not engage in further distribution of this material or use it for any profit-making activities or any other form of commercial gain. Politicising Europe’s Justice Deficit: Some Preliminaries Michael A. Wilkinson LSE Law, Society and Economy Working Papers 8/2014 London School of Economics and Political Science Law Department Politicising Europe’s Justice Deficit: Some Preliminaries Michael A. Wilkinson * Abstract: Normative political theory is divided on whether questions of distributive justice properly extend beyond the state. From a functionalist perspective, however, justice reflects a balance of material forces, subject to the logics of ‘market’ and ‘social’ justice, or ‘capitalism’ and ‘democracy’. The justice ‘deficit’ is the imbalance or disequilibrium in these logics, an imbalance which the constitution of the post-war European state stabilises through their constraint. European integration, initially an important feature of this post-war settlement, now increasingly comes to be viewed as a significant threat to it. Whereas market logic and capital have been rapidly supra-nationalised, social-democratic logic has struggled to transcend the state, the EU, in particular, lacking the channels of contestation to legitimise redistribution. This leads to an imbalance in the forces of capitalism and democracy, a justice ‘deficit’, which destabilises national as well as supranational institutions, but also leads to questions being asked of what Germans owe Greeks, or vice versa. The justice deficit and reaction to it now appear to be threatening core features of state sovereignty. But it also suggests that the logic of the state – and the question: to whom are obligations owed? – must itself be subject to contestation; the dilemma of market and social justice, or capitalism and democracy, must be replaced with a trilemma, of market, social and democratic justice. * Associate Professor of Law, London School of Economics and Political Science. I would like to thank, with more than the usual disclaimer, Floris de Witte, Samuel Tschorne, Alexander Somek, Hans Lindahl and Jacco Bomhoff for comments on an earlier draft. A revised version of this paper will appear in D. Kochenov, A. Williams and G. De Burca (eds) Europe’s Justice Deficit? (Hart, 2014, forthcoming). I would like to thank the editors for their invitation, patience and encouragement. 8/2014 2 Today owners of financial capital are working with international organisations and debt-ridden national states to insulate once and for all the economic economy from the moral economy of traditional social obligations and modern citizenship rights – and with greater prospect of success than ever in the four decades since the 1970’s. As democratic states are being turned into collection agencies on behalf of a new global haute finance, market justice is about to prevail over social justice, for a long if not an indefinite period of time. In the process those who have placed their confidence as citizens in capitalist democracy must concede precedence to those who have as investors placed their money on it. [Wolfgang Streeck, ‘How to Study Contemporary Capitalism’ (2012) 53 European Journal of Sociology 15-16.] INTRODUCTION Europe is awash with deficits. In addition to the various economic deficits engulfing the Eurozone (and elsewhere), the EU has been said to suffer a democratic deficit, a political deficit and a social deficit, each of which predates the financial and subsequent sovereign debt crises beginning in 2007.1 None of this is new to the seasoned observer of the EU. Only now, however, is discussion turning to its ‘justice deficit’. Not merely pointing to the aggregate of these other deficits, accusation of a justice deficit suggests something more fundamentally rotten at the heart of the project. Justice, after all, is the sovereign virtue.2 Even if it is curious that the measurement of this virtue is now expressed in the language of economics – a justice ‘deficit’ – the very measure of the EU in terms of its justice, or rather, injustice – which is where the accusation points – suggests that a threshold has been crossed. After all, dominant strands in the analytical tradition of normative political theory have not infrequently resisted or outright rejected its applicability to domains beyond the nation-state – including the nascent EU polity – due to the absence there of the relevant political community.3 Other commentators continue to justify the political, democratic and 1 On the democratic deficit, see S. Hix and A. Follesdal, ‘Why there is a Democratic Deficit in the EU: A Response to Majone and Moravscik’ (2006) 44 Journal of Common Market Studies 533; on the political deficit, see R. Dehousse, ‘Constitutional Reform in the EC’ in Hayward (ed.) The Crisis of Representation in Europe (Abingdon, Frank Cass, 1995); on the social deficit, see C. Joerges and F. Roedl ‘Informal Politics, Formalised Law and the Social Deficit of the European Union’ (2009) 1 European Law Journal 1-19. 2 Analysis of Europe’s justice deficit could proceed by investigating the treatment of refugees and asylum seekers, allegations of complicity in torture and processes of extraordinary rendition, collusion in wars and occupation of dubious legality, mass surveillance programs and other threats to civil liberties. None of this will be dealt with here. 3 See e.g. T. Nagel, ‘The Problem of Global Justice’ (2005) 33 Philosophy and Public Affairs 113. Michael A. Wilkinson Politicising Europe’s Justice Deficit: Some Preliminaries 3 social deficits beyond the state or to deny them normative significance in the first place.4 The purpose here is not to engage directly in debates over the correct theory of the reach and scope of justice claims, over the respective merits of libertarianism and egalitarianism or over the precise limits of the polity within which one may properly speak of justice or injustice. It is rather to consider the way that European integration is altering – whether by exposing, concealing or constraining – the politics of justice; in particular, the way integration is destabilising the national frame but not (yet) offering up an alternative platform for subjecting transnational justice claims to democratic contestation. There is a reason for taking an explanatory rather than a normative approach. Whatever normative theory of social justice we happen to endorse (including its wholesale rejection),5 the distribution of individual, collective and common goods will in practice, in any really existing society, be determined, at least in part, by political and social struggles for equality. This means not only over the economists’ ‘scarce resources’ but also over public goods such as education and health and non-material goods such as solidarity, recognition and representation.6 Since in democratic society ideological superiority will – in theory at least – always be up for grabs, arguments of principle in favour of or against redistribution, recognition and representation will merely be another factor in the fight over and for such goods. Wolfgang Streeck has recently modelled struggles over distribution on the tension or ‘dynamic disequilibrium’ between capitalism and democracy, where they are understood not as organised competitions for the accumulation of money or votes but as representing two principles or logics of resource allocation - market justice and social justice. This enables us to conceptualise a justice deficit as the result of an imbalance in these two logics. And, in Streeck’s account, imbalance will tend towards crisis, provoking a reaction of sorts to remedy the imbalance or at least prevent it from becoming critical for the society (section 1).7 But in what context is this relationship played out? The contest between market and social justice does not occur in a vacuum. Historically, it is the state that sets the framework for the negotiation and recalibration of the relationship between market and social justice, through institutional and ideological, coercive as well as consensual means (section 2). 4 See e.g. J. Neyer, ‘Justice, Not Democracy: Legitimacy in the European Union’ (2010) 48 Journal of Common Market Studies 903. 5 On the rejection of patterned theories of justice, see R. Nozick, Anarchy, State, Utopia (New York, Basic Books, 1974). 6 Only in part because in practice levels of inequality will depend not only on the basic structure of the state, and its reception to political and social struggles, but also on what has been called the principle of community, the extent to which questions of distributive justice arise for persons in their daily lives. See e.g. G. Cohen, ‘Back to Socialist Basics’ (1994) New Left Review 3. 7 See W. Streeck, ‘Taking Capitalism Seriously: Towards an Intuitionalist Approach to Contemporary Political Economy’ (2011) 9 Socio-Economic Review 137; W. Streeck, ‘How to Study Contemporary Capitalism?’ (2012) 53 European Journal of Sociology 1; W. Streeck, ‘The Crises of Democratic Capitalism’ (2011) 71 New Left Review 5; W. Streeck, ‘Markets and Peoples’ (2012) 73 New Left Review 63. 8/2014 4 In recent historical perspective, the political constitution of the post-war state has been conceived as aiming to prevent or forestall crisis by constraining the logics of democracy and of capitalism.8 On this account, the process of European integration is a significant feature of the post-war settlement – designed to prevent majoritarian democratic excesses but without surrendering the state’s ability to constrain the logic of capitalism (section 3).9 But European integration is now exposing the fragility and dysfunctionality of this settlement. With the apparent boundlessness of markets and extension of market logic, but with democracy struggling to transcend state borders, the structural asymmetry in Europe is now proving destructive, not only of the supranational constitution but also of national constitutional settlements. We can conceptualise the EU’s ‘justice deficit’ as representing this imbalance in favour of capitalism and market justice, where, in the absence of a European democratic or social movement, any rebalancing is to come from the executive power of the member states, or rather from certain among them (section 4). And yet, whatever the prospects of supra- or trans- national democracy, Europe’s justice deficit is de-politicised with market logic presented in naturalistic terms, making it appear necessary and inevitable, an expression of inescapable pressures to modernise and gain competitiveness. It will be argued that pre- requisite to dealing with the justice deficit is its politicisation. But this may come at a high cost in terms of the stability and unity of the project of integration, and is (therefore) unlikely to come from the top-down, from the political and economic elites who have driven the project since its inception (section 5). I will suggest in the concluding section (6), drawing on the recent work of Nancy Fraser, that ‘the state’ – understood as the framing of relevant boundaries – must itself be politicised, subject to contestation and struggles of recognition and representation. The challenge, it is argued, is to substitute Streeck’s dilemma for a trilemma, of market justice, social justice and democratic justice. The purpose of this paper is not to proffer institutional responses to this trilemma, nor even to specify its social and political conditions; it is to explore some preliminaries for a fuller understanding of the politics of Europe’s justice deficit. 1. CONCEPTUALISING A JUSTICE DEFICIT A justice deficit can be explained functionally as the result of an imbalance between the logic and forces of capitalism on the one hand and those of 8 I draw here on the work of Jan-Werner Müller, Contesting Democracy: Political Ideas in Twentieth Century Europe (Yale University Press, 2011). 9 Chris Bickerton’s argument that the post-war logic fundamentally changes in the neo-liberal period beginning in the 1970’s will also be drawn upon, see C. Bickerton, European Integration: From Nation-States to Member States (Oxford, OUP, 2012). Michael A. Wilkinson Politicising Europe’s Justice Deficit: Some Preliminaries 5 democracy on the other. A social justice deficit would then exist where the former gains an upper hand over the latter. A compelling account of this imbalance – or ‘dynamic disequilibrium’ – between democracy and capitalism has recently been presented by Wolfgang Streeck.10 He argues that the relationship between capitalism and democracy will tend towards a critical imbalance as capital tends to dominate, and to such an extent that democracy itself will be threatened, as revealed most dramatically in Europe since the recent financial crises. In Streeck’s account, capitalism and democracy, or ‘markets’ and ‘peoples’ represent rivalling constituencies, with contrasting ‘logics of action’, which we can label as ‘market justice’ and ‘social justice’ respectively.11 In terms of societal values, these suggest two different principles of resource allocation: one operating according to marginal productivity, and merit on a ‘free play of market forces’ and the other based on social need, and ‘certified by the collective choices of democratic politics’.12 This reflects a clash in the respective ethical demands of the two major forces in the modern democratic capitalist state, rather than merely a functional clash of interests between money and votes. If the market imposes a marginal ethics (by advancing the prospect and expectation of rational egoism and competitive accumulation without limits), democratic society promises a maximal ethics (by holding out the prospect of and need for solidarity, collaboration and concern for human well-being).13 By rejecting the standard contrast between an amoral market system and moral obligations of solidarity, persons and political communities are in this account instead torn between obligations on either side of the justice balance, obligations that although distinct are not incommensurable. On the one hand, market imperatives present individuals and communities with the duty to adopt and adjust to economic change, to accumulate wealth, to be entrepreneurial in spirit, competitive, and, above all, efficient. On the other hand, democracy calls forth solidarity, the collective obligation to protect weaker individuals from the fallout of capitalist excesses and to prevent or attenuate the ‘creative destruction’ that is central to liberal progress or ‘modernisation’; debate then occurs ‘over the moral limits, if any, to the pursuit of economic advantage’14 where that pursuit and its limits are themselves understood as normative forces. The paradox is that the market ethos of a capitalist political economy is, for reasons of systemic survival, parasitic upon the moral obligations imposed by social democratic norms.15 By tempering and correcting capitalist excess, these prevent disequilibrium from turning into outright societal collapse. 10 See note 7 above. 11 A. Schäfer and W. Streeck ‘Introduction’ in A. Schäfer and W. Streeck (eds.), Politics in the Age of Austerity (Cambridge, Polity, 2013) 19. 12 Streeck, ‘Crisis of Democratic Capitalism’, note 7 above, 7. 13 Streeck, ‘Taking Capitalism Seriously’, note 7 above, 137. 14 Streeck, ‘How to Study Contemporary Capitalism?’, note 7 above, 23. 15 Id. But, Streeck notes, ‘only in a functionalist worldview’ is the success of efforts at taming capitalist excesses actually ‘guaranteed’, note 7 above, 156. 8/2014 6 There is therefore an interdependence rather than straightforward conflict between the two principles of resource allocation. But this is not a happy or stable relationship. As Streeck concludes, capitalism not only necessitates a continual demand for moral and social support in order for the system to stay afloat, but it is also always undermining that very same support because of its own internal logic. Because of this pathological tendency, capitalism is an inherently ‘self-destructive social formation’.16 Democratic capitalism is then conceivable ‘as a political economy in permanent disequilibrium’, pushed forward inexorably by continuous innovation on the part of capital and ‘pervasive political conflict over the relationship between social and economic justice’. Disequilibrium will periodically lead to crisis, not least because of the inability of capital to think beyond its own short-term interests; even the environmental conditions of our survival are reducible to a mere ‘externality’. With this relationship in view, capitalism is systematically reconfigured, because profits and losses – as well as resultant gulfs in socio-economic equality among persons – are exposed as non-naturalistic, ‘the outcome of a struggle between conflicting concepts of and claims to justice […]’ rather than between an irrational moral code and an amoral but rational objective economic law.17 Rational and public choice philosophy then appear in a new light; rather than purely scientific, positivistic theories that remain above the political fray, they can be seen as performative and ideological, imposing a dominant market logic and narrow view of rationality on neighbouring disciplines and occluding alternative values. Self-interest is the only proper mode of rationality, and, eventually, ‘greed is good’. This subordination of discourses of legitimacy to a particular economic rationality is achieved through ‘naturalising’ the logic of the market. The technocratic dictates of economics then come to speak ‘with the pathos of natural law’, controlling and even colonising the political debates over justice and inequality.18 Economics is the method; the aim is the transformation of the soul.19 2. HISTORICISING A JUSTICE DEFICIT: THE ROLE OF THE STATE Although recent political philosophy in the social contract tradition investigates justice primarily as a normative question, seeking for a resolution or reflective 16 Streeck, ‘How to Study Contemporary Capitalism?’, note 7 above, 25. 17 Streeck, ‘How to Study Contemporary Capitalism?’, note 7 above, 16. 18 G. Teubner, Constitutional Fragments (Oxford, OUP, 2012) 32-34. For Teubner, the neo-natural law conception of economic rationality is nothing less than ‘grotesque’ because it substitutes causal explanation for normative legitimacy, bypasses political debate, and overlooks the potential instability of a constitution based on science that has to resolve controversies which cannot be scientifically resolved. 19 To misquote Margaret Thatcher. Michael A. Wilkinson Politicising Europe’s Justice Deficit: Some Preliminaries 7 equilibrium, Streeck’s analysis exposes it as an irresolvable, practical, political problem. This becomes even more apparent when attention is given to the unit within which the question of justice is properly raised, which is frequently, but often implicitly, assumed to be a state.20 And the standard reason given, if one is given at all, is that only within the state does the requisite unity of coercion and community exist, generating and sustaining the capacity to provide for basic collective goods.21 Although in some apparent degree of tension with each other, coercion and community are presented as complementary rather than in competition. Both are paradigmatic attributes of statehood. First, the capacity to dominate, the monopoly on legitimate violence, which in the Weberian tradition is the defining feature of the modern state and in liberal political theory key to understanding why its authority requires normative justification, is, at least formally, an exclusively sovereign power. To this must be added, second, the sense of being part of a collective endeavour or ‘community of fate’, necessary for sustaining a functioning public sphere and legitimising any non-trivial redistribution of benefits and burdens. This too is elusive once we move beyond the state’s borders. Only by combining these features in a contiguous manner, when a state not merely coerces but does so ‘in our name’ or for our collective benefit, are obligations to remedy injustice and duties of redistribution incurred, above the minimum moral duties of humanitarian intervention that might exist outside the state. We ought to be concerned with equality because, and when, we can and do value the reciprocity that it entails. The unity of coercion and community is therefore central to the modern state’s capacity to negotiate the tension between capitalism and democracy, market and social justice. Since beyond the state there is no (or at most – as in the case of the EU – only relatively ineffective) political apparatus that unites coercion and community, there can be no egalitarian duties of redistribution.22 But from a political perspective, this tension is not resolved in an original position or final determination of where the balance of justice rests; rather the state provides a more or less stable framework within which the ceaseless competition and interaction of interests and ideas might be negotiated relatively peacefully.23 In practice the state manages the tension between capitalism and 20 In Rawls’s later work, exploring the international basic order, the relevant unit is explicitly a ‘people’; see J. Rawls, Law of Peoples (Cambridge MA, Harvard University Press, 1999). 21 In Nagel’s ‘political conception’ it is coercion and co-authorship that combine as the relevant characteristics giving rise to obligations of justice within a state, against the cosmopolitan account, see note 3 above. Nagel’s position is not of course unchallenged, see e.g. A. Julius, ‘Nagel’s Atlas’ (2006) Philosophy and Public Affairs 176 - 192. And there are those in the Rawlsian tradition who have argued for a more cosmopolitan or global basic structure. 22 We may, however, have moral duties to create such authoritative institutions (and mechanisms of redistribution) in the first place. 23 I do not claim that the state is merely a neutral arbiter between these forces; it is undoubtedly more complex than that. Beyond some suggestive comments, this will not be the place to go into detail into the history and concept of the state and its role in the balance of justice. 8/2014 8 democracy in order to contain or forestall any crisis that might result from the imbalance in their relationship. From this perspective, coercion and community are also instrumental to the maintenance of stability in spite of, and even to legitimise existing and continuing, inequality. The idea of a community of fate, binding rulers and ruled, not only facilitates redistribution but also softens, if not eradicates, class conflict. It pacifies struggles over justice by appealing to a sense of communal identity, which is not merely left to grow spontaneously or organically, even if it could be nurtured in that way. This is periodically revived as a political project – however insincerely – with communitarian mottos such as that currently in vogue, ‘we are all in it together’, and ironically by those who only recently urged that ‘there is no such thing as society’. From a functional perspective, recall, resources of solidarity are a necessary complement to a market economy, to maintain or re-establish order either by rebalancing the justice disequilibrium or encouraging the population to tolerate, accept or at least acquiesce in the inequalities that the market permits, and even depends upon. In the absence of such resources of solidarity, politics will require more coercive mechanisms. There is, to be sure, nothing new in the perception that the tense and even antagonistic relationship between market and social justice, capitalism and democracy, has a significant political dimension. In an earlier period, Karl Polanyi argued that the destruction caused by the dis-embedding of the market in a liberal capitalist society would lead to a reaction, or ‘second movement’, of re-embedding through social policies and the re-regulation of markets.24 It is not only that as a matter of proper sociological understanding, the economy is embedded in society rather than the other way round; it is also that politically, since democracy poses a threat to the logic and interests of capital, the ruling class will attempt to curtail the economic goals of the majority, and by political and even constitutional means if necessary.25 The perception that capitalism and the individualist ethos of classical liberalism pose a serious threat to the robust ‘public’ on which democracy itself depends, as John Dewey argued in a different historical and political context, has a similarly vintage pedigree. Dewey of course thought that democracy must permeate all of society, becoming industrial and not merely civil and political; in order to allay the corrupting effects of capitalism and the inequalities it results in, a vibrant public is essential.26 24 K. Polanyi, The Great Transformation: The Political and Economic Origins of Our Time (Boston, Beacon Press, 2001). 25 ‘Inside and outside England, from Macaulay to Mises, from Spencer to Sumner,’ wrote Karl Polanyi in The Great Transformation, first published in 1944, ‘there was not a militant liberal who did not express his conviction that popular democracy was a danger to capitalism’. Ibid 234. 26 See e.g. J. Dewey, The Public and Its Problems (New York, Henry Holt, 1927). By focusing on the potential of science and experimentation, Dewey arguable neglected the politics necessary to contain capitalism, see M. Wilkinson, ‘Dewey’s Democracy without Politics: The Failures of Liberalism and Frustrations of Experimentalism’ (2012) Contemporary Pragmatism 117 - 142. Michael A. Wilkinson Politicising Europe’s Justice Deficit: Some Preliminaries 9 And the framing of the justice deficit is political in a second and more basic sense that calls into question any statist assumptions. Although the ‘Keynesian- Westphalian’ co-evolution of a monopoly of legitimate violence and a community of fate is difficult to envisage beyond the state, it would be an error to think and act as if the state were therefore self-contained or insulated for the purposes of negotiating the tension between capitalism and democracy, market and social justice. Coercion, it must be remembered, can be and frequently is exercised between states and even through international institutions that lie over and above states. Both capitalism and democracy are linked to projects of state- and institution-building, both at home and abroad, most obviously in the guise of foreign and imperial adventures, however civilising their missions in the eyes of those who pursued them. Neither coercion nor community, in other words, is autonomous and independent from political action, internally or in external relations. The framework of assumptions that implied a hermetically sealed national container was of course long ago shattered historically by exposing the links between political freedom, capital accumulation, and imperialism. As Arendt powerfully argues in ‘The Origins of Totalitarianism’, political emancipation of the bourgeoisie in the late nineteenth century was prompted by their desire for economic expansion, which in turn necessitated expanding the territorial logics of power beyond the nation-state.27 In addition, the assumed role of the bourgeois state and state-sponsored ideology in protecting the security of the individual – determining its openness or closure towards immigration, fixing policies of asylum and assimilation, formulating citizenship tests as well as labour and welfare policies towards foreigners – demonstrates that the internal framework within which democracy and capital ‘slug it out’ is not fixed in regard to the outside world, but contingent on politics and political action. Restricting the domain of justice to relations within the state has the effect of legitimising the ‘de facto’ inequality that exists between states, as if any inequality beyond the state was apolitical, natural, or beyond the domain of human action. Just as it is a mistake, in other words, to see the state only as an enabler of social justice or as an impartial arbitrator of the balance between markets and peoples, it is also a mistake to view it as an arbitrary but necessarily neutralised pivot of the balance of justice. All of which is to say that the logics of market and social justice do not exist in a vacuum, and so to Streeck’s account must be added the political context of their interaction. As a glance at the historical record confirms, to the longevity of the functional disequilibrium must be added its evolution through distinct stages of economic and political development, including, particularly in the second half of the twentieth century in which the project of European integration is born, 27 H. Arendt, The Origins of Totalitarianism (Harcourt, (1951) 1968) 123 - 157. More recently it has also been argued that it is predominantly Western imperialism and intrusion into the Arab world, rather than religious fundamentalism that is the root cause of the alienation felt by Muslims in Europe today. See P. Anderson, ‘Portents of Eurabia’ The National, 2009. 8/2014 10 significant institutional and ideological elements which constrain the logics of capitalism and democracy, and in a way that is not captured by the bare categories of coercion and community. 3. HISTORICISING A JUSTICE DEFICIT: THE ROLE OF IDEOLOGY In the postwar period in Western Europe, as classical economic models based on notions of unfettered competition and free markets are replaced with those of late, or ‘organised’, capitalism based on intervention with market mechanisms, tolerance of oligopoly and the generation and sustenance of large public sectors, government intervention in recalibrating the relationship between democracy and capitalism comes to be taken for granted. This continues to be the case to this day, even if rhetorically and opportunistically dismissed or derided by the cheerleaders of neo-liberalism, which does not hesitate to embrace the authoritarian state apparatus if necessary. Whether to ensure the smooth functioning of a market economy, assuage the financial markets, or on more radical accounts, continue the process of accumulation through dispossession, ensuring the continuation of the inequalities on which capitalism depends, governmental interference on both sides of the justice balance is ubiquitous.28 But not only is the economy increasingly and explicitly entangled with institutions of political democracy and state bureaucracy; struggles over market and social justice also assume more complex political and ideological forms, in part due to the reaction to the series of crises that engulfed Europe and elsewhere in the first half of the twentieth century, in the forms of fascism and Soviet communism. Social, political and economic struggles in the post-war State are tempered by what has been called ‘constrained democracy’ and ‘constrained capitalism’, collective commitments – often of a constitutional nature - which encourage or impose limits on the democratic and capitalist logics, in order for the society to maintain stability and avoid the extremism that potentially occurs as society relapses – or appears to be in the process of relapsing – into crisis. 29 First, in Jan-Werner Müller’s narrative of post-war democracy in Europe, distrust of popular sovereignty and even parliamentary sovereignty was ubiquitous in the aftermath of World War II, with the goal of constraining democratic majorities uppermost in the minds of political and bureaucratic elites, to prevent backsliding into the authoritarian extremism that devastated Europe in the first 28 See further, M. Wilkinson, ‘The Spectre of Authoritarian Liberalism: Reflections on the Constitutional Crisis of the European Union’ (2013) German Law Journal 527 - 560. 29 See further, exploring the history in various national contexts, J-W. Müller, Contesting Democracy (Yale University Press, 2011). Michael A. Wilkinson Politicising Europe’s Justice Deficit: Some Preliminaries 11 half of the twentieth century.30 This distrust of politics, and fear of both Right and Left was manifested in concrete national institutions, with liberal constitutionalism and strong constitutional courts in particular developing across the region, most notably in the Federal Republic of Germany, but complemented with supranational institutions in the EU (or EEC as it then was) and the ECHR.31 Not only economically, but also institutionally, this was the hour of the ‘European rescue of the nation-state’, in Alan Milward’s well-known narrative.32 But second, there was also, from the beginning of the post-war period until at least the mid-1970’s and the dawn of the neo-liberal revolution, a Keynesian consensus on the need to protect society from the excesses of capitalism and market justice.33 As well as laying the foundations of the social security or ‘welfare state’, this involved a bargain or social contract between capital and labour, a post- war ‘class compromise’, obtained by a set of mediating institutions, which attempted to organise capitalism in such a way that would unite state and society.34 This strengthening of the bonds between state and society, and between business and labour, was complemented by a commitment to the collective pursuit of broader social goals, including economic development, technical innovation, full employment, regional income distribution, and national security.35 ‘Socialism’, according to Müller, ‘had been implemented from above to constrain capitalism’ or as Tony Judt puts it, to save it.36 Politically, it was the ‘moment of Christian Democracy’ and other elite-led and state-sponsored ideologies that pushed for the attainment and entrenchment of stability by curtailing political extremism and avoiding economic imbalances and excessive levels of socio-economic inequality.37 Constitutional and international commitments, internally and within the architecture of European legal regimes, increasingly ‘take things off the table’ for democratic contestation, at least if one wants to play within the rules. And of course the two dimensions of constraint – ideological and institutional – act most effectively in tandem in alleviating the perceived dangers of democratic and capitalist excesses. The project of European integration was considered a significant means to achieve this, internalising transnational externalities and softening the potential for 30 Ibid. And on the recent Euro crisis, see J-W. Müller, ‘Beyond Militant Democracy?’ 44 (2012) New Left Review 239. 31 Müller: ‘European integration – this is crucial – was part and parcel of the new ‘constitutionalist ethos’, with its inbuilt distrust of popular sovereignty and the delegation of tasks to agencies that remained under the close supervision of national governments’, ibid. 32 A. Milward, The European Rescue of the Nation-State (London, Routledge, 1992). 33 This was, Tony Judt, notes, an ‘unusually broad consensus’ on this, T. Judt, Ill Fares the Land (Penguin, 2010) 47. 34 See C. Bickerton, European Integration: From Nation-States to Member-States (Oxford University Press, 2012). 35 Ibid, 107. 36 Ibid, 47. 37 Müller describes Christian Democracy as ‘the most important ideological innovation of the post-war period, and one of the most significant of the European twentieth century as a whole’, in Contesting Democracy, above, note 29, at 130. The UK does not fit so neatly in this pattern; attaining relative stability and socio-economic equality in the postwar period but without constraining parliamentary supremacy. 8/2014 12 sovereign violence. Along with the economic benefits thought to accrue from reducing obstacles to trade through the creation of a common market, this was the most convincing rationale for the state’s voluntary ‘containment’ and surrender of ‘limited sovereign rights’.38 European integration initially was considered a key aspect of the postwar constitutional settlement, a central feature in the narrative of the survival of the democratic sovereign state through constraining its dominant logics. Unlikely to transcend the nation-state or represent its evolution into a federal state writ large, because of the difficulty – let alone questionable desirability – of up-scaling the required combination of coercion and community, the EU would instead be an additional bulwark against the dangers of political and economic excesses. The process was complemented from its early stages by a strong and proactive juridical project to create a transnational rule of law, based on subjective, and predominantly economic, rights. A glance at the subject matter of the foundational and even revolutionary case of Costa v. ENEL – often lost in the mist of the supremacy doctrine it gave birth to – is revealing: an Italian law that sought to nationalise electricity production and distribution, based on the disputed payment of a 1, 925 Italian lire bill.39 This ideological and institutional neutering of democratic and market logics was complemented by a ‘golden age’ of sustained economic growth, which facilitated the (temporary) satisfaction of the demands of both capital and labour, dramatically reducing levels of socio-economic inequality.40 The precise contribution made by European integration to the peace and prosperity of the ‘Trente Glorieuses’ is contested. What is not contested is that from the mid-70’s, coinciding with an end to easy economic growth, the ‘long downturn’, equilibrium between capitalism and democracy has become more difficult to maintain.41 38 For recent accounts of the argument from containment within EU free movement law and citizenship, see F. De Witte, ‘Sex, Drugs & EU Law: The Recognition of Ethical and Moral Diversity in Europe’ (2013, forthcoming) 50 Common Market Law Review and ‘Union Citizenship and Constrained Democracy’ in A.P. Van der Mei and M. De Visser (eds) Twenty Years Treaty on European Union: Reflections from Maastricht (Intersentia, 2013). 39 Case 6/64 Costa v ENEL [1964] ECR 585. The case was spearheaded by two members of the Italian bar actively pursuing the project of creating a European rule of law; see e.g. A. Vauchez, ‘The Transnational Politics of Judicialisation. Van Gend en Loos and the Making of EU Polity’ (2010) European Law Journal 1-28. 40 According to Bickerton: ‘The decades of prosperity were tied to a particular model of both state and society and a specific understanding of the relationship between politics and economics’, above note 34, at 93. 41 Financially, one solution was thought to be allowing high inflation, which can be seen as ‘an expression of anomie in a society which, for structural reasons, cannot agree on common criteria of social justice;’ a second then increasing credit: first government debt, then private credit, in both cases ‘pulling future resources into present consumption’. If this accumulation of private and public debt foregrounds the most recent financial crisis, one current response in the UK at least is, it appears, more of the same: another debt-fuelled and state-assisted housing bubble. See Streeck, ‘Crises of Democratic Capitalism’, above n 7, 23. So-called ‘privatised Keynesianism’, which is advanced as the immediate cause if not the ultimate root of the current economic crisis, is suggested by Streeck as a concession to the democratic pressures exerted by the people. This highlights an ambiguity in Streeck’s account. Historically ‘privatised Keynesianism’ was not, arguably, a response to democratic pressure but to capitalist pressure. For one Michael A. Wilkinson Politicising Europe’s Justice Deficit: Some Preliminaries 13 The forces of market justice have, in this period of neo-liberal ascendancy, come out firmly on top, creating a further critical imbalance in the relation between capitalism and democracy. The current period of crisis demonstrates once again how the state is called on dramatically to intervene, but, in doing so with austerity for the poor and primarily in order to regain international competitiveness under pressures of market justice, is doing so with scant regard for socio-economic equality and considerations of distributive or social justice. What kind of further democratic response, if any, this might lead to, remains to be seen. In the brief aftermath of the collapse of the Soviet Union, the idea of the co- originality and co-evolution of democracy and capitalism took hold of our collective imagination, a marriage that signified, on some accounts, no less than the end of history itself.42 Contributing to this eschatological sentiment in Europe was a narrative that paired wider integration with waves of democratisation and market liberalisation, as first Spain, Portugal and Greece emerge from political dictatorship to join the common market and later the countries of the former Soviet bloc apply for membership of the EU. And the ‘Copenhagen criteria’ for membership of the EU in the 1990’s made the pairing of democracy, the rule of law and human rights with a functioning market economy both formal and explicit conditions.43 Any sense of having reached the plateau of liberal democratic constitutionalism was not to last long, however, as, well before the recent financial crisis, the EU began to face a more inward looking constitutional crisis of legitimacy, expressed both in popular rejection of the Constitutional Treaty and in juridical resistance to the constitutional jurisprudence of the European Court of Justice.44 Both global and European narratives of a comfortable reconciliation of democracy and capitalism have now, in any case, been exposed if not completely exploded. Not least the role of the state has increasingly resumed centre stage, even if neo-liberalism has proved surprisingly ideologically resilient, as well as economically and politically powerful.45 thing, it occurred most intensely in places where the working class was being weakened – with the neo- liberal war on the unions waged by Reagan and Thatcher. Does Streeck’s argument imply that without democratic pressures, capitalism would exist in a natural equilibrium? That markets would be self- correcting if left to themselves, unperturbed by democratic pressure? For a different account of the golden age and subsequent ‘long downturn’ see R. Brenner, The Economics of Global Turbulence (London, Verso, 2005), emphasising the significance of the global unevenness and competition between national capitalisms. 42 The reference of course is to Francis Fukuyama, The End of History and the Last Man. For more nuanced accounts, rejecting both the internal relation and internal tension between capitalism and democracy, see e.g. P. Wagner, The Crisis of Democratic Capitalism: Reflections on Political and Economic Modernity in Europe, LEQS Paper 44/2011 and before the recent crisis, A. Touraine, What is Democracy? (Westview Press, 1997). 43 Laid down at the June 1993 European Council meeting in Copenhagen. 44 The strongest resistance in terms of influence has been from the German Constitutional Court. See e.g. D. Grimm, ‘Defending Sovereign Statehood Against Transforming the Union into a State’ (2009) European Constitutional Law Review 353. 45 See C. Crouch, The Strange Non-Death of Neo-Liberalism (London, Polity Press, 2011). 8/2014 14 Obituaries for an end of history thesis already deconsecrated by its own author are unnecessary, which is not to say we have definitively moved beyond its paradigms. But however resilient the modern liberal state, the crises and contradictions of democratic capitalism have undoubtedly escaped its confines, becoming Europeanised and globalised, most apparently in the latest economic crises in the Eurozone, which of course were set in motion by events on the other side of the Atlantic.46 So too the site of struggle between market justice and social justice has now shifted, at least partially, beyond the state, being played out between electorates and financial institutions, governments and international organisations. 4. FRAMING THE EU’S SOCIAL JUSTICE DEFICIT Through the evolution of political and legal institutions in the EU, both coercive and consensual aspects of political rule would emerge beyond the state, even if only in incipient form. But this gradual outsourcing of political authority and of constitutional checks and balances, rather than protecting the Keynesian- Westphalian ‘nation-state’, now threatens rather to transform it, into a post- Westphalian ‘member state’.47 There are many aspects to the erosion of the national political frame and the demise of its social-democratic Keynesian compromise; the precise role that the EU has played in this narrative is far from straightforward. And to be sure, our specific judgment may vary depending on which of the varieties of capitalism from amongst the various Member States we take as our exemplar.48 Even on a single state, the effects of European integration may vary over time, as laws and institutions at national and supranational level themselves evolve. The purpose of Streeck’s account was, however, to suggest that, despite the possibility and actuality of regional variation in terms of the precise political construction of and response to the capitalist economy, there is a singular logic and ethic of capitalism and market justice, which not only can be abstracted from its varieties, but is integral to its institutional and ideational form. And, however persuasive the varieties of capitalism literature in comparative context, there is a strong current of opinion, in states as varied in their political and constitutional economies as the UK and Germany,49 which holds that 46 For an account of this single globalised crisis of financial capitalism see e.g. M. Aglietta, ‘European Vortex’ (2012) 75 New Left Review 15. 47 See Bickerton, note 34 above, chapter 2. I borrow the term Keynesian-Westphalian from Nancy Fraser. 48 See e.g. P. Hall and D. Soskice (eds.) Varieties of Capitalism. The Institutional Foundations of Comparative Advantage (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2001). 49 In the UK context, see D. Nicol, The Constitutional Protection of Capitalism (Oxford, Hart, 2010); in the German context see F. Scharpf, ‘The Asymmetry of European Integration: or Why Europe Can’t Have a Social Market Economy’ (2010) 8 Socio-Economic Review 211. Michael A. Wilkinson Politicising Europe’s Justice Deficit: Some Preliminaries 15 European integration has been a significant factor in the erosion and even overall demise of the ‘Keynesian-Westphalian’ compromise due to the structural asymmetries that the EU creates and maintains.50 Institutions and practices of social justice, both public and private, at the national level, if not found disproportionate in their effects on trade, may become a burden of comparative disadvantage due to the effects of competition and free movement norms. The juridification of the default rules of free circulation of the factors of production in the EU, combined with the political difficulties of re- regulation or even Treaty amendment (in areas where the EU lacks competence), particularly in light of the consensus politics with which it operates, favours and even entrenches a firmly, if not unambiguously, neo-liberalising trajectory.51 Idiosyncratic features of supranational integration not only combine to prevent cogent political-democratic response to the social dysfunctionality of the market but also deter the creation of possibilities for such response: a central bank unable to buy government debt and bound to the single objective of ensuring price stability, the relative lack of labour mobility due to cultural and linguistic heterogeneity, unprecedented wage repression in the largest economic bloc, an eclectic mix of economic development and bureaucracies in different phases of modernisation, and above all the (real or perceived) absence of a supranational community of fate.52 The structural asymmetries imposed by Europe’s peculiar brand of federalism tips any balance of justice overwhelmingly in favour of market and against social justice, pushing the dynamic disequilibrium of democratic capitalism to tipping point. There are simply insufficient channels of contestation to generate the social and political legitimacy for any Polanyian double movement at the supranational level that might correct these biases and imbalances. Although there is a powerful and growing body of academic opinion to say that political union must now ultimately ensue, either to deal with the German question or to resolve the Greek problem,53 the EU emphatically has not itself followed in the footsteps of the statist model or developed a fully-fledged transnational social contract. Arenas of distributional conflict are becoming ever more remote from domestic politics, but the imperative to upscale the democratic political framework for the negotiation and re-negotiation of justice claims has been resisted.54 The political response to redistributive questions in Europe – to 50 It is Fritz Scharpf, above all, who has conceptualised and described in institutional detail the social and economic imbalances caused by Europe’s constitutional asymmetry. See recently, on the role of European law in this process, F. Scharpf, ‘The Asymmetry of European Integration: or Why Europe Can’t Have a Social Market Economy’ (2010) 8 Socio-Economic Review 211. And for a broader examination of this asymmetry in the terms of constitutional theory, see N. Walker, ‘The Place of European Law’, in J. Weiler and G. DeBurca (eds) The Worlds of European Constitutionalism (Cambridge, CUP, 2011). 51 See Scharpf’s exhaustive analysis of the asymmetry between market and social rules, law and politics in the EU, ibid. 52 See P. Anderson, ‘After the Event’ (2012) 73 New Left Review 49 – 61. 53 See e.g. U. Beck, A German Europe (Cambridge, Polity Press, 2013). 54 Streeck, ‘Crises of Democratic Capitalism’, n 7 above, 27. 8/2014 16 questions of social justice not only within but also between states – has occurred, if at all, sotto voce, behind the backs of the electorates. If taking market logic and market justice beyond the state has been celebrated in Europe in an era of ordo- and then neo-liberalism, taking democracy and social justice beyond the state has proven theoretically and practically problematic, to say the least.55 Democracy, it is only too clear, has not become fully supra-nationalised in response to the freedom of capital and other factors of production to roam beyond borders. And if the democratic deficit in the EU was already notorious, it has now become critical, with constraints placed on the core of national democratic sovereignty in the ESM and ‘Fiscal Compact’.56 And yet, on the dominant ordo-liberal account, the asymmetry of European integration was entirely justified: the supposed virtues of inter-state competition and the perceived economic benefits of the free circulation of goods, workers, and capital better attained without political interference.57 Founded on ‘guarantees of economic freedom’, the EU’s legitimacy - according to a leading figure in the ordo-liberal school - is quite ‘independent’ of its ‘democratic and socio-political future.’58 From a market liberal perspective, moreover, the absence of a ‘demos’ represented a solution rather than a problem: our reduction to ‘mere’ individuals, ‘consumers’ or ‘entrepreneurs’, is motivated by perfect economic rationality. An economic constitution celebrates the absence of a ‘demos’ because political redistribution of wealth, whether unjustified or merely irrational, is less likely to be feasible in the absence of community or social solidarity, a ‘we-feeling’ amongst the members of a polity.59 Ordo-liberalism, in tune with its neo-liberal cousin, ‘has more confidence in the economic constitution than in democracy.’60 This divorce of political authority from control over economic resources leaves market justice to triumph over its rival. But it is now becoming clear that not only would the EU fail to develop the political capacity to deal with perceived injustice across its borders, it would also impede the existing states from reconciling their own tensions and the writing and re-negotiation of their own social contracts: 55 For an account of the political traits of neo-liberalism, see D. Harvey, A Brief History of Neo-Liberalism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007). 56 ‘Treaty Establishing the European Stability Mechanism’ (ESM), July 11, 2011, O.J. (L 91) and the ‘Treaty on Stability, Coordination and Governance in the Economic and Monetary Union’ (‘Fiscal Compact’) http://www.european-council.europa.eu/eurozone-governance/treaty-on-stability?lang=en, last accessed on 16 January 2014. For analysis, See e.g. See M. Dawson and F. De Witte, ‘Constitutional Balance in the EU after the Euro-Crisis’ (2013) 76 Modern Law Review 817. 57 The ordo-liberal account of the EU is presented by Ernst-Joachim Mestmacker, see e.g. ‘European Touchstones of Dominion and Law’ (2007) The Ordo Yearbook of Economic and Social Order 4. On regulatory competition, see A. Sayde, ‘One Law, Two Competitions: An Enquiry into the Contradictions of Free Movement Law’, (2011) Cambridge Yearbook of European Legal Studies, 365-413. 58 Mestmacker, ibid, 7. 59 Hayek favoured a form of interstate federalism to assuage the perceived threat of redistribution. For discussion, see A. Somek, ‘The Social Question in a Transnational Context’, LEQS Papers, 39/2011. 60 J. Habermas, The Crisis of the European Union: A Response (London, Polity Press, 2012) 129. Michael A. Wilkinson Politicising Europe’s Justice Deficit: Some Preliminaries 17 the construction of Europe as an economic and monetary union, without corresponding political and fiscal integration, disabled the protective capacities of member-states without creating broader, European-wide equivalents to take up the slack. Today, the evidence is all around us: Greece is reduced to a protectorate, Spain, Portugal and Ireland are ruled from Brussels, and central bankers set limits to domestic policy even in Germany and France. The upshot is that the project of social protection can no longer be envisioned in the national frame.61 Regarding the national level, there is a strong case to say that whatever was left of the Nordic model of welfare capitalism after the neo-liberal onslaught of the late 1990’s has been further undermined by the rulings of the court of justice in its recent case-law on the free movement of establishment and freedom to provide services.62 Far from the European rescue of the nation-state, the EU now seems to be in the process of contributing to its transformation. The sense of a serious imbalance between capitalism and democracy, caused or exacerbated at least in part by Europe’s constitutional asymmetry, is becoming increasingly pervasive. Jürgen Habermas, an otherwise avid if not stubborn supporter of the project of integration, now notes that ‘political management’, ‘uncoupled’ from the democratic pressures and dynamics ‘of a mobilised political public sphere and civil society’, is deprived of the motivational strength to resist capitalism, unable ‘to contain and redirect’ its ‘profit-oriented imperatives’ into ‘socially compatible channels’. As result, governing authorities increasingly ‘yield’ to the neo-liberal pattern of politics: A technocracy without democratic roots would not have the motivation to accord sufficient weight to the demands of the electorate for a just distribution of income and property, for status security, public services, and collective goods when these conflicted with the systemic demands for competitiveness and economic growth.63 Market discipline had been supposed to perform the function of stabilising economic systems, to compensate for the merely soft, symbolic sanctions against fiscal excess in the Stability and Growth Pact (violated almost immediately by France and Germany)64 and for the ‘no bail-out’ rule enshrined in the Treaty (Article 125 TFEU) that prevented, in theory, transnational sharing of the burdens 61 N. Fraser, ‘Triple Movement’ (2013) New Left Review 126. 62 For recent analysis, see e.g. E. Christodoulidis, ‘The European Court of Justice and “Total Market” Thinking’ (2013) 14 German Law Journal 2006. 63 J. Habermas, ‘Democracy, Solidarity and the European Crisis’, lecture delivered at Leuven, in April 2013, a full transcript is accessible at: http://www.kuleuven.be/communicatie/evenementen/evenementen/jurgen-habermas/en/democracy- solidarity-and-the-european-crisis, last accessed on 16 January 2014. 64 A violation side-stepped by the Court of Justice in Case C-27/04 Commission v Council. 8/2014 18 of any economic crisis, until the Court rules otherwise in its Pringle decision.65 But soft measures are now to be substituted for the harder rules contained in the ESM and ‘Fiscal Compact’.66 Although, strictly speaking, these take place outside the EU acquis, they threaten the constitutional balance of the European Union, by calling into question the most cherished principles of integration – democracy, Member State equality, the balance of powers, the ‘community method’, and even respect for the rule of law itself.67 If the EU was destined to become a civilised, ‘non-imperial Empire’,68 then the financial crisis and responses to it are threatening to tear away this thin veneer of respectability. Disorder, in the present critical conjuncture has spilled over from the economic to the political domain, upsetting not only the ‘system integration’, but also the ‘social integration’ of contemporary societies, as the life- world becomes increasingly precarious, with austerity programs, in the southern Europe in particular, wrecking lives. Not only is political democracy in practice suspended in debtor countries, but the economic constitution itself is bypassed, because of the imperatives of the financial markets and the concerns of creditor states.69 And where that is the case, as, arguably, it already is in countries like Greece, Ireland and Portugal, ‘street riots and popular insurrection may be the last remaining mode of political expression for those devoid of market power’.70 This tampering with an already precarious equilibrium threatens to explode – if not already detonated – into outright revolt in Europe. If there was already a democratic deficit in Europe, there is now a crisis of democracy. And because of the power – real or imagined – of the troika and even the credit rating agencies themselves, citizens increasingly perceive their governments, ‘not as their agents, but as those of other states or of international organisations’,71 who utilise the messages sent by the financial markets to control and cajole if not to coerce their populations. The financial markets, we are increasingly informed, will simply not tolerate certain political outcomes, or more often, political indecision, giving new lease of life to the sentiment that ‘time is money’.72 And international organisations, such as the IMF and the European Union, are ‘immeasurably more insulated from electoral pressure than was the traditional 65 Case C-370/12, Pringle v Ireland. For analysis, see A. Menendez, ‘The Existential Crisis of the European Union’ (2013) German Law Journal 453 - 526. 66 Note 51 above. 67 See M. Dawson and F. De Witte, above note 56. 68 In the words of Jose Manuel Barroso, see http://www.brusselsjournal.com/node/2244, last accessed on 16 January 2014. 69 See C. Joerges, ‘Europe’s Economic Constitution in Crisis and the Emergence of a New Constitutional Constellation’, available at http://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2179595#, last accessed on 16 January 2014. 70 Streeck, ‘Crises of Democratic Capitalism’, n 7 above, 28. 71 Streeck, ‘Crises of Democratic Capitalism’, n 7 above, 26. 72 Accredited of course by Max Weber to Benjamin Franklin. Michael A. Wilkinson Politicising Europe’s Justice Deficit: Some Preliminaries 19 nation-state’.73 Whereas in the post-war constitutional settlement this insulation (or democratic constraint) was considered one of the EU’s supposed strengths – and in the ordo-liberal account, a real virtue – it is now increasingly being perceived as a disruptive and dangerous vice. As a result, extreme nationalist political parties prosper, with promises, however unrealistic, to regain the harnesses of power and smash the mythical power of fate, personified now by faceless bureaucrats and troika representatives. The need to ‘re-embed’ the market economy has been exploited by reactionary movements of right-wing populism rather than transnational movements of pan- European solidarity. The promise of regaining collective autonomy, which only appears institutionally possible at the national level, however illusory in practice, is a far from unattractive platform from which to gain popular electoral support. 74 In the wake of the financial crisis, we have witnessed the results of capitalism acting ‘more like itself’, with capital movement and market justice having increasingly strained at the leash of democratic and territorial controls. And in the absence of a European demos and democratically legitimate European institutions, it is not markets themselves but strong states that appear to take up the slack, however reluctantly, to ensure the survival of transnational capitalism and the market economy. In this way, the financial crisis has not only revealed the fragility of the constitutional principles of the EU; it has also exposed a horizontal asymmetry between larger and smaller member states, or economically stronger and economically weaker states, that was previously concealed. So although strong statehood is lacking at the supranational level, there is at least one contender at the national level, which in conjunction with technocratic governance structures in the EU has been able to call the shots: the Federal Republic of Germany.75 In the absence of political channels of contestation, dictats and coercive measures prevail. And they appear to emanate from one source in particular. As Perry Anderson puts it, In the European simulacrum of federalism, there could be no ‘transfer union’ along American lines. Once crisis struck, cohesion in the Eurozone could only come, not from social expenditure, but political dictation—the enforcement by Germany, at the head of a bloc of smaller northern states, of draconian austerity programmes, unthinkable for its own citizens, on the southern periphery, no longer able to recover competitivity by devaluation.76 Coercive elements of rule are becoming increasingly prominent and exposed, from the centralised supranational authority and its representatives in the Commission 73 Streeck, ‘Crisis of Democratic Capitalism’ n 7, above, 26. 74 This is most evident in Greece with the rise of Golden Dawn. Greece is perhaps unique in also giving rise to a major new left-wing and anti-austerity party, Syriza, which, although maintaining support for the Eurozone was considered a threat by the liberal establishment, particularly in Germany. 75 See e.g. Beck, note 53 above. 76 Anderson, note 52 above. 8/2014 20 and European Central Bank, to international organisations such as the IMF, 77 as well as among the Member States themselves. Real economic power discrepancies are even becoming translated into political norms, as is the case of the voting weights in the European Stability Mechanism.78 European integration not only adds an additional layer of complexity to the relationship between democracy and capitalism; it also makes the core tension more visible. It exposes the justice deficit in broad daylight and the coercion necessary to sustain the background conditions of transnational economic order. Preventing conflict from becoming critical and destructive of the project of the Euro must, we are told, be achieved at all costs. The post-war narratives of ‘constrained democracy’ and ‘constrained capitalism’ therefore appear to be coming to an abrupt end in the current phase of European integration. And, in a conjuncture of exquisite irony, it seems that the constitutional model of the European Union is to be forcefully remade due to the political and economic strength of the one country that integration was supposed above all to contain. Mann’s nightmarish vision of a ‘German Europe’ rather than a ‘European Germany’ is in danger of becoming a reality.79 5. POLITICISING JUSTICE DEFICITS There are many attempts to justify the institutional responses to the financial crisis, to suggest, for example, that they are necessary temporarily, in the short- term, to ensure the stability of the integration process, or at least its currency, in the long run. There have been attempts to justify the constitutional asymmetries and justice deficits in the EU. Some also deny that European integration creates, contributes to or maintains such deficits at all. But it is becoming increasingly difficult to persuade persons, and indeed entire peoples, that integration merely expands the pie for all, that there are not real transnational redistributive implications of membership in the EU or even that they remain in collective control of their fates. And many influential commentators now argue that Europe will need to engage in huge and explicit redistributive programs and therefore develop into full political union in order to deal with the social and economic effects of the recent financial crises.80 But in the absence of the requisite transnational solidarity to support this democratically, openly and voluntarily, the emergency ‘rescue operation’ is being 77 For analysis of the institutionalisation of this ‘troika’, see Menendez, note 65 above. 78 See De Witte and Dawson, note 56 above. 79 See Beck, note 53 above. 80 See e.g. Offe, ‘Europe Entrapped: Does the EU Have the Political Capacity to Overcome its Current Crisis’ (2013) European Law Journal 595 – 611. Michael A. Wilkinson Politicising Europe’s Justice Deficit: Some Preliminaries 21 conducted in an ‘undemocratic, depoliticized, and technocratic mode’.81 This raises the danger of new forms of authoritarianism emerging, both nationally and transnationally.82 A recalibration of the ‘moral calculus’ of integration – of transnational solidarity – will not however to come top-down from elites, but, if at all, from the recognition by the peoples of Europe of the injustice of those suffering from the austerity measures being imposed upon them. 83 The justice deficit, however, is frequently de-politicised by naturalising the ascendency of market justice. There is, for example, a strong tendency to perceive the initial movement of capitalist logic and market justice in quasi-naturalistic terms, as an unstoppable social and evolutionary force, which democratic politics can do nothing more than attempt to tame or civilise in response. This perception of the capitalist economy as natural and autonomous is most explicit and developed in systems theory and can be traced back through to Weber’s rationalisation thesis of modernity, and even beyond, to the natural law understanding of the economy that substitutes the state for civil society, in the work of thinkers such as Adam Smith and Thomas Paine. De-politicisation of the public sphere finds support in elite theories of democracy and systems theory, because, in common with the classical doctrines of political economy, they appeal to an evolutionary narrative of social reproduction, whether normatively or merely descriptively. 84 Common to these varied positions is the viewpoint that the economic is not only autonomous; it is foundational for the polity and for political development.85 It is a view that even (sympathetic) critics of Weber such as Jürgen Habermas have come to adopt.86 Since the fall of the Berlin wall and the collapse of the Soviet Union, he claims, it has become ‘impossible’ to break free from the world of capitalism; ‘the only remaining option is to civilise and tame the capitalist dynamic from within’.87 And the transformation of law and politics in the process of European integration, Habermas argues, is bound up with this capitalist dynamics, framed by a ‘functionally driven opening’ of integration and inclusion followed by a ‘socially integrative closure’, or re-embedding of the market.88 There is a broader point here. Escape from democratic politics signalled by the practice and discourse of ordo- and neo-liberalism is not new; its sentiment is as old as philosophy itself. Liberalism’s attempt to escape from politics through 81 Offe, ibid. 82 See Wilkinson, above note 28. 83 The term ‘moral calculus’ is Offe’s, see note 80 above. 84 For Weber, rationalisation is an aspect of our loss of freedom in modernity, see, for discussion, e.g. K. Breen, ‘Under Weber’s Shadow: Modernity, Subjectivity and Politics’ in Habermas, Arendt and MacIntrye (Ashgate, 2012). On Smith and Paine, see e.g. M. Loughlin, Foundations of Public Law (Oxford, OUP, 2010) 347. Teubner’s work is an important exception here, providing a critique of the naturalisation of economic rationality from within systems theory; see note 18 above. 85 Foucault identifies this reversal as central to understanding neo and ordo-liberalism. See M. Foucault, The Birth of Bio-Politics: Lectures at the College de France (London: Palgrave MacMillan, 2010). 86 Cf. Breen, note 84 above. 87 Habermas note 60 above, 106. 88 ibid, 113. 8/2014 22 economics, as Hannah Arendt argued, is not a departure, but a continuation of the philosophical tradition that begins with Plato and ends with Marx.89 Once a substitute for action is found – which is traditionally the role of the ‘absolute’, in modern times Sieyes’ nation or Jefferson’s self-evident truths – politics becomes mere administrative execution, analogous to the private economic decisions of the household. The loss of the political comes with the identification of a source of authority ‘beyond the sphere of power’ and, whether the law of nature or the commands of God, not itself ‘man-made’. The source of authority apparently ‘beyond the sphere of power’ and therefore beyond the sphere of democratic politics is now the market itself and global capital markets in particular, their authority anonymised in the form of barely comprehensible and virtually unaccountable credit rating agencies. The suggestion of the ‘naturalness’ of any existing order and the inequalities in which it results is ideologically potent, particularly when it is accompanied by an ethos of competition and an individualism that might be attractive for other moral or cultural reasons.90 The high water-mark of this reification of the capitalist economic logic is the neo-liberal insistence that ‘there is no alternative’ (TINA), propagated so forcefully by Margaret Thatcher that it was swallowed whole not only by her Conservative but by her ‘Third Way’ successors, in the UK and elsewhere.91 Can the justice deficit be politicised or re-politicised? This, it is argued, is a condition for it to be democratised, however democratisation might then be institutionally imagined and implemented. Although this will not of course convince those who deny there is a social justice deficit at all in the EU, it remains, if correct, a contribution to an account of why social (or market) justice deficits are in large measure political artefacts, whether or not they exist in any particular place at any particular time. The struggle for social justice must be viewed not only in terms of the possibilities of reacting through existing channels to the (actual or perceived) injustice perpetuated by market capitalism but in terms of the creation of markets and of the channels of response to them in the first place. We can then consider in particular the way that politics facilitates or hinders a democratic response to that actual or perceived injustice as well as its complicity in the initial movements of market making and inducing the extension of market logic. 89 See H. Arendt, Between Past and Future (Penguin, 1968) 17 – 19. The point is made as strongly in The Human Condition (University of Chicago, 1958) 222: ‘Escape from the frailty of human affairs into the solidity of quiet and order,’ Arendt notes, ‘has in fact so much to recommend it that the greater part of political philosophy since Plato could easily be interpreted as various attempts to find theoretical foundations and practical ways for an escape from politics altogether’. 90 On the supposed natural quality of the economic order in neo-liberalism, see e.g. M. Foucault, The Birth of Bio-Politics: Lectures at the College de France (London: Palgrave MacMillan, 2010), O. Parker, Cosmopolitan Government in Europe (London: Routledge, 2012). On how neo-liberalism splits the left, by co-opting liberal social causes, see Harvey, above note 55. 91 Thatcher, when asked to name her greatest legacy, famously responds, ‘Tony Blair’. Michael A. Wilkinson Politicising Europe’s Justice Deficit: Some Preliminaries 23 Politicisation of the justice deficit points at how capitalist market logic depends upon the state and on political action not only for its maintenance and ‘taming’, but also for its creation and re-creation. This can occur both through action and inaction. It suggests that the state is at once both problem and solution to the crises of democratic capitalism; both poison and cure. According to a radical philosophical tradition, the state apparatus is not only responsible for an initial, often violent, movement of original or ‘primitive’ accumulation that sets up the economic and social conditions for market capitalism (Marx’s ‘doubly free labourer’), but also constantly or periodically re- constitutes these conditions through ‘accumulation by dispossession’.92 But others – including those less radical – have identified political action, coercion and violence, whether through internal corruption, war or in the form of global imperialism (‘political capitalism’), as central to at least some types and certain periods of market formation and continuing in aspects of modern capitalism.93 Violence, coercion and imperialism, however, are only contingently necessary to alter the balance of forces between democracy and capital. In the most recent era of neo-liberalism, to the conceptual dynamic of social and market justice must also be added political and legal changes made to and by the State which tip the balance between democracy and capitalism in favour of capital, such as the hollowing out of state powers, the turn from government to governance, whole- sale privatisation programs, the removal of issues from the democratic agenda and into the regulatory arena of experts and technocrats and constitutionalisation – and therefore judicialisation – of economic rules, particularly through international institutions.94 There is a strong affinity between privatisation and regulation on the one hand and technocratic, expert government on the other, and of course in the EU this was captured by Majone’s notion of the ‘regulatory state’, although it is also an aspect of the ideology of ‘constrained democracy’ that we explored above.95 There was, and is, nothing inevitable about the turn to the regulatory state; it is the expression of political choices and planned structures. Placing the political and its most potent manifestation, the modern state, at the root of the political economy of capitalism (whether classical, late or ‘post-modern’) and the seemingly inexorable spread of market logic, highlights the contingency of the market as an economic and normative form, however powerfully articulated and cultivated institutionally and ideologically. As Joseph Weiler acknowledged with respect to the process of market-building as the centerpiece of European integration: 92 See D. Harvey, The New Imperialism (Oxford, OUP, 2003); E. Meiksins Wood, Empire of Capital (London, Verso, 2003). For an earlier account, see Arendt, note 27 above, 148, drawing on Rosa Luxemburg. 93 Such as Max Weber himself, with his category of ‘political capitalism’. See e.g. R. Swedberg, Max Weber and the Idea of Economic Sociology (1998) 46 - 53. 94 See e.g. S. Gill, Power and Resistance in the New World Order (London and New York, Macmillan-Palgrave, 2003), D. Nicol, The Constitutional Protection of Capitalism (Oxford, Hart, 2010), W. Bonefeld, ‘Neo-Liberal Europe and the transformation of democracy’ in Nousios, Overbeek and Tsolakis (eds) Globalisation and European Integration (London, Routledge, 2011). 95 See G. Majone, Regulating Europe (London, Routledge, 1996). 8/2014 24 A “single European market” is a concept which still has the power to stir, but it is also a “single European market”. It is not simply a technocratic programme to remove the remaining obstacles to the free movement of all factors of production. It is at the same time a highly politicised choice of ethos, ideology and political culture: the culture of “the market”[…] premised on the assumption of formal equality of individuals […] Crucially, this not only accentuates the pressure for uniformity, but also manifests a social (and hence ideological) choice which prizes market efficiency and European-wide neutrality of competition above other competing values.96 Of course de-politicisation was in some sense a deliberate choice in the designs of the various European communities, which favoured consensual over conflictual evolution, at least the consensus of powerful political and economic elites.97 The transnational economy would be based on legal guarantees, technical regulations and even ‘soft laws’ such as the Stability and Growth Pact, rather than centralised political controls subject to democratic contestation. One might say, adopting Weiler’s influential narrative, that it was based on this combination of law and technocracy precisely because political controls remained with the Member States, reluctant to surrender them, particularly in the early stages of integration.98 But once the political nature of transnational market logics is acknowledged, then alternatives to the fundamentals of the current set-up – and not merely tinkering around the edges – might be explored as a genuine possibility. The crisis is, in any case, already exposing the weakness of the rule of law in the face of political response to economic emergency, as developments in the grey zone of the Union method evolve, although it is too early yet to say precisely what this portends.99 6. DEMOCRATISING THE JUSTICE DEFICIT? The ‘Keynesian-Westphalian’ negotiation of market and social justice through a combination of ‘constrained capitalism’ and ‘constrained democracy’ can no longer be taken for granted, if not already consigned to the history books.100 We have sketched the role that European integration has played in this negotiation 96 J. Weiler, ‘The Transformation of Europe’ (1991) Yale Law Journal 2477. 97 For an account, see M. Dani, ‘Rehabilitating Social Conflicts in European Public Law’ (2012) 18 European Law Journal 621 – 643. 98 Ibid. 99 See A. Menendez, note 65 above, for the long view. 100 Müller himself thinks we have recently turned a corner and that the EU has changed qualitatively, no longer able to lock in states to democratic and social commitments, see ‘Beyond Militant Democracy’ (2012) 73 New Left Review 39. Michael A. Wilkinson Politicising Europe’s Justice Deficit: Some Preliminaries 25 and its transformation, although of course it is a story that touches on all the states of the democratic capitalist world. The effect of globalisation and Europeanisation has been ‘to destabilise’ the existing structures of political claims and to change the dynamics of market and social justice.101 With this destabilisation, even explosion, of the national frame, the assumption no longer holds that the modern territorial state is the exclusive site of justice claims. Neither is it clear that the citizens of such states are exclusively the relevant subjects of debates about justice. As Nancy Fraser argues, not just the ‘what’ but also the ‘who’ of justice must now be up for grabs.102 This is nowhere more evident than in contemporary Europe, where integration now directly raises the question of what, if anything, Germans owe Greeks (or vice versa), either as the result of a ‘moral calculus’ of integration or for the benefit of their own long-term self-interest. In addition to the usual first order questions of distribution and recognition within a particular community, second-order questions are increasingly being raised about justice in the EU. Not only the substance of justice, but also the ‘frame’ is increasingly in dispute, and demands are increasingly being made for a post-Westphalian theory of justice.103 And yet, in recalling the priority of politics we cannot ignore the question of the political, or le politique, which, fundamentally, defines the parameters of who is to be counted amongst the members of the relevant community, and, in its most infamous formulation, between who is friend and enemy.104 The point is not merely to highlight the priority of action and contingency over decisionism and necessity, because, as Fraser herself acknowledges, the political ‘furnishes the stage on which struggles over distribution and recognition are played out’. She continues: Establishing criteria of social belonging, and thus determining who counts as a member, the political dimension of justice specifies the reach of those other dimensions: it tells us who is included in, and who excluded from, the circle of those entitled to a just distribution and reciprocal recognition.105 The framing of ‘the political’ determines not only who can make justice claims, by virtue of establishing who is a member of the relevant community, but also how such claims are to be made, judged and acted upon, and of course the precise procedures are significant because they not only exclude certain voices, but also 101 See N. Fraser, ‘Reframing Justice in a Globalizing World’ (2005) New Left Review 69. 102 Ibid. 103 Fraser, note 101 above, at 73. 104 C. Schmitt, The Concept of the Political (University of Chicago Press, 1927), 2007. For an account of European constitutionalism which gives priority to the political, but in more dynamic and reflexive terms, see M. Wilkinson, ‘Political Constitutionalism and the European Union’ (2013) 76 Modern Law Review 191 – 222. 105 Fraser note 101 above, 75. 8/2014 26 privilege some interests over others in stipulating the rules and conditions of access. Political justice is therefore concerned chiefly with the idea and the practice of representation, where misrepresentation would point to the distinctively political obstacles to equality of representation, in addition to in justice presented by maldistribution and misrecognition within a polity. Misrepresentation can occur at the first ordinary, domestic level of the democratic process, where, for example, the rules and internal constituencies of the electoral system itself are drawn. This is far from straightforward in a compound polity such as the EU, which has to balance the basic principle of the equality of persons with the more complex principle of the equality of states, because the constitutional identity of the component parts matters.106 A balance is sought through the electoral system of the European Parliament, with its system of degressive proportionality, engagement with national parliaments, and in conjunction with forms of indirect representation through the European Commission and Council. Although this balance is difficult in any federal or compound polity it has special resonance in the EU because of the continuing sovereignty claims of the constituent parts, as so forcefully articulated, however disingenuously, by the German constitutional court in the Lisbon decision, which insists on maintaining the constitutional power to guarantee its own social state.107 Misrepresentation can also occur at a second level, which concerns the basic boundary-setting aspect of ‘the political’. Here misrepresentation takes the form of mis-framing, where the injustice is not insufficient representation but wrongful exclusion from any kind of political representation. Although the process of economic globalisation exposes this mis-framing because it reveals our inter- connectedness in a more comprehensive and immediate manner, it must be remembered, with Arendt, that the Keynesian – Westphalian frame itself mis- framed in significant respects, with political emancipation tied in with legacies of capitalist expansion and imperialism.108 If political obstacles to full and fair representation existed within the Keynesian – Westphalian frame of the territorial state, European integration - and economic globalisation more generally - exposes the injustice of the frame itself, because those affected by it are marginalised from its political decision-making centres in spite of the legal and political equality they are formally attributed. The enhanced possibility of political gerrymandering comes at the expense of the marginalised and powerless, who can only, if at all, channel their claims through relatively ineffective political channels. The allocation of votes in the European Stability Mechanism, weighted by capital contributions, is a good example of the 106 See e.g. C. Lord and J. Pollak, ‘Unequal but Democratic? Equality According to Karlsruhe’ (2013) 20 European Journal of Public Policy 190 – 205. 107 For a critique of the German court’s understanding of political equality see Lord and Pollak, ibid. 108 See note 27 above. Michael A. Wilkinson Politicising Europe’s Justice Deficit: Some Preliminaries 27 normalisation of the conflation of economic and political power, which has potentially dramatic effects on the principle of political representation. Europeanisation and globalisation are politicising the normal Westphalian frame of justice by making a dimension of injustice more visible. A special kind of meta-injustice is exposed, where some are wrongly excluded from consideration, ‘denied the chance to press first-order claims’ within a community.109 Metapolitical misrepresentation arises when states and transnational elites monopolize the activity of frame-setting, denying voice to those who may be harmed in the process, and blocking creation of democratic arenas where the latter’s claims can be vetted and redressed. The effect is to exclude the overwhelming majority of people from participation in the meta-discourses that determine the authoritative division of political space.110 In the EU, those who consider their voices silenced by processes beyond their individual and even collective control will take to the streets instead, as we have seen from Athens to Madrid and from Lisbon to Paris. But, one might ask, in the new light of the redistributive implications of economic and monetary union, why is it that the political code is still predominantly nation versus nation? What explains the absence or weakness of transnational social movements in comparison to the power of transnational capital? Is it a straightforward failure of elites? To begin to answer this, a third element of social struggle must be explored, working alongside economic and social justice, in order to appreciate the full complexity of the justice deficit: ‘emancipation’. Really existing social struggles do not neatly fit the contours of a Polanyian double movement or of Streeck’s rebalancing of the relationship between market and social justice. Instead they have exposed problems not only with marketisation and the spread of market logic but also with the socially protective responses to it that, in the name of social justice, have depended on an exclusionary rhetoric of communitarianism, homogeneity and popular consensus.111 Struggles for emancipation are now cross- cultural, transnational, plural and heterogeneous; from feminism to the anti-war movements, Occupy to trade unionism, environmentalism to the indignados, the voices of social justice are diverse and dispersed.112 A politics of representation must ‘aim to democratize the process of frame- setting’,113 to contest the way in which boundaries themselves are drawn. This is 109 Fraser, note 101 above, 77. 110 Fraser note 101 above, 85. 111 On the exclusion and sovereign violence of the social contract model See Parker, above n 90. 112 See the report on subterranean politics. In the eyes of the Habermas-Derrida initiative, it was the anti- war movements coordinated on 15 February against the invasion of Iraq that gave birth to a European public sphere. See ‘February 15, Or What Binds Europeans Together’ reprinted in (2003) 10 Constellations 291 – 297. 113 Fraser, note 101 above, 80. 8/2014 28 no easy task.114 But what it suggests is that to the tension between the logics of democracy and capitalism must be added the logic of the state, and its external and internal manner of setting the scene for this ceaseless antagonism of interests and values, including the shaping of transnational political spaces such as the EU. Streeck’s dilemma of market and social justice must be substituted for a trilemma: of market, social and democratic justice. Only then might the destabilisation of the national frame signal democracy’s graduation rather than its retirement. 114 This is an area, however, where democratic experimentalism has presented certain insights about the need to keep open, contingent and provisional the form and content of the democratic community. work_ltwlja44k5errovidrbambfyo4 ---- Whose Justice? Rethinking Transitional Justice from the Bottom Up ������� �� �� �� ��� ��� ������ ��� ������ �� ���� ���� ���� ���������� ��� ��� !� ����� ���� �� ���� � � ��� � � � �� ���� � ���� ��� ������ �� �������� �� �� � ��� ������ �� ���� ����� �� �� ���� �������� ��� � ����� ����� � �� �� � �������� ��� �� ���� ��� � ������� � � ������� � ������������� ������� ���� �� � ��� � ��� �� � ����������������� ���� ��� � ��� � �� ���� �� � ��� �� � �� ����� ��� ������� �� ������ �� � ������ ������������ �� � ��� �������� ��� � ����� � ������� ��� ����� ���� � ��� ������ ����� � � ���� ������ �������� ��� � ����� �� � ��� � � �� ������ ������� � �������� � ��� ����������� � ��� � ��� � ����� �� �� �� ��� �� ��������� � ������� ���� ���������� �� � �� �������� ��� � ����� ���� � ���� ��� � ����� ���������� � � ��� ������ � � � ��������� ������ ! " ������ ������� ���������� #��� !�� ��� $ ���� ���� � � ����% ���� �� �&�� ��� ��������� ��� ������� � � � � �� �� � ��� ��� ������ � �� ���� ��� ���� � �� �������� � ����� �� � � �������� ��� � ����� ��� ������ � �� � ��� �������� � ��� ��������� � �� �� � ������� �� � ����� � ���� ��� ��������� ��� ����� ��� ������ ���� �� ���� � ��������� �� ����� ����� �� ���� ��� ���������� �� ��� �� �� ������� � �� ������� �� ������� ��� ���� ����� �� �������� ��� � ������ ���� ��� �� "#$ "#% &''( )*+(', $"' -�*%$�)*(./+)$ #0'(,#1 "#% +$% 2**$% +( $"' �'#)' .2#3'4*25 ,'6'/*�', +( $"' �(+$', �#$+*(1% �')2'$#27 8'('2#/ �*9$2*% �*9$2*%�8"#/+1% -�0'(,# .*2 :'#)'1 ;!!�� ; ( $"+% �#�'2 4' #,6#()' $"' ��� � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/� :9&/+%"', &7 �/#)54'// :9&/+%"+(0 �$,� !��� 8#2%+(0$*( �*#,� �<.*2, ��= � >� �? #(, ��� �#+( �$2''$� �#/,'(� �� ��;=�� ��� @ '��������� � ( �� � �� )��������� � )������ * ������ ��� "��� ������ +�,- ./+� " ������ ������� ��� ���0 ��������� � @@ '��������� � ( ���� ��� ���� � ���� (�������� 1� � 2��� )���������� (� 2����� 3 ��� 4������� 5,6 7/ � 1� ���� �� ����0�� ��������� � ; !� ! ���� � � ����8 ������� � '��� ����� ��������� ��� ���������� A;!!�B ;C �� *)� �D=CD�CC��D�=;;;� 6+'4 $"#$ # 02#%%2**$% #��2*#)" $* $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' %"*9/, &' 2'0#2,', #% #( +($2+(%+) �#2$ *. $"+% #0'(,#� �"' +($'2(#$+*(#/ )*339(+$7 "#% 2')'($/7 �2+*2+$+F', E9%$+)' +%%9'% #(, +% .+(#()+(0 #(, %9��*2$+(0 $"' +3�/'3'($#$+*( *. # �/'$"*2# *. /'0#/ +(+$+#$+6'%� �% *(' )*33'($#$*2 (*$',� ,'6'/*�3'($ )*�*�'2#$+*( "#% &''( 2'.*239/#$', +( /'0#/ $'23% #(, 3*2' #(, 3*2' +($'2(#$+*(#/ '..*2$ "#% 0*(' +($* &9+/,+(0 )*92$%� 42+$+(0 /#4%� �9(+%"+(0 �'2�'$2#$*2% *. "93#( 2+0"$% #&9%'%� %9��*2$+(0 "93#( 2+0"$% �8�%� #(, 0'('2#//7 �2*3*$+(0 $"' 29/' *. /#4 #&2*#,� � A�'�B'%$#&/+%"+(0 $"' 29/' *. /#4 +% (*4 2'0#2,', #% # �2'2'G9+%+$' .*2 $"' '3'20'()' *. %$#&/' #(, �'#)'.9/ %*)+'$+'% #(, E9%$+)' �#)5#0'% #2' .2'G9'($/7 �#2$ *. ('0*$+#$', �'#)' #02''3'($%� H*4'6'2� $"'2' +% # 02*4+(0 ,'&#$' #&*9$ $"' #��2*�2+#$' 3*,'/ #(, /'6'/ A.*2 '<#3�/'� $"' 0/*&#/� (#$+*(#/� /*)#/D)*339(+$7B #$ 4"+)" $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' 3'#%92'% %"*9/, &' #,*�$',� #(, 4"'$"'2 $"'%' #2' )*3�/'3'($#27 *2 6+#&/' #/$'2(#$+6' �2*)'%%'%� � �2+$+)% "#6' #209', $"#$ /#4 +% +()2'#%+(0/7 %''( &7 $"' +($'2(#$+*(#/ )*339(+$7 #% *(' *. $"' %#.'%$ 4#7% +( 4"+)" $* '(0#0' 4+$"� *2 +($'26'('� +( *$"'2 )*9($2+'%� �9)" #$$'3�$% $* -+(./9'()' $"' 29/'% *. $"' 0#3'1 '6+,'()' $"' .#)$ $"#$ +($'2(#$+*(#/ E9%$+)' #(, 29/' *. /#4 +(+$+#$+6'% #2' (*$ �*/+$+)#//7 ('9$2#/� = ( �#2$+)9/#2� $"' $'(,'()7 $* '<)/9,' /*)#/ )*339(+$+'% #% #)$+6' �#2$+)+�#($% +( $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' 3'#%92'% +% # �2+3#27 ./#4� 2#+%+(0 .9(,#3'($#/ G9'%$+*(% *. /'0+$+� 3#)7� /*)#/ *4('2%"+�� #(, �#2$+)+�#$+*(� �+3�/7 +(6*/6+(0 /*)#/ �'*�/' #$ $"' +3�/'3'($#$+*( %$#0' *. $"'%' +(+$+#$+6'% +% (*$ '(*90"� �*2 # .9//7 �#2$+)+�#$*27 �2*)'%% A4' 4+// #209'B $"'7 %"*9/, #/%* $#5' �#2$ #$ '6'27 %$#0' +( $"' �2*)'%% +()/9,+(0I )*()'�$+*(� ,'%+0(� ,')+%+*( 3#5+(0� #(, 3#(#0'3'($� �"' #+3 *. $"+% �#�'2 +% $* '<#3+(' )2+$+)#//7 %*3' *. $"'%' +%%9'%� #(, 4"+/' 3+(,.9/ *. $"' ,#(0'2% *. *6'2�'9/*0+F+(0 # �#2$+)+�#$*27 #��2*#)"� '<�/*2' $"' 6#/9' *. �#2$+)+�#$+*( #(, /*)#/ #0'()7 .*2 $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' $"'*27� �*/+)7� #(, �2#)$+)'� $ +% %$29)$92', +( %+< �#2$%� �+2%$� +$ &2+'./7 '<#3+('% $"' *2+0+(% *. $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' #(, +$% #��/+)#$+*( +( �*%$�)*(./+)$ %*)+'$+'%� �"+% +% .*//*4', &7 # &2+'. #%%'%%3'($ *. %*3' *. $"' 5'7 ��� � �� �*5"+&'2� 5 ��� �����������8 9 ��� � !�� � ��� * ����� (��� � A����B ; ;�� � �� �'$$%� -�"*9/, ���2*#)"'% $* :*%$�)*(./+)$ �9%$+)' #(, �')*()+/+#$+*( &' '$'23+(', 8/*&#//7� �#$+*(#//7 *2 �*)#//7J1 A����B ;C 1 � ���� *� � '���� ����� 3������� C�� ��I �� �+)5.*2,� -�(*..+)+#/ �29$" :2*E')$%1� 9(�9&/+%"', �#�'2 *( .+/' 4+$" #9$"*2% A����BI :� 82'#,7� -�')*()'�$9#/+F+(0 $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)'� '3&',,', #(, ,+%$#()', E9%$+)'1 A����B � $ ������� (�� ���� : '���� ����� � �;I :� �9(,7 #(, �� �)8*6'2(� -�"' +#/*09'% +$"+(� �'3*27� �*339(+$7 #(, :*%$��*(./+)$ �2#(%+$+*( +( # �#$+*(#/+%$ �*339(+$7 +( $"' �*2$" *. 2'/#(,1� �#�'2 �2'%'($', $* -�9/$92'% *. :*/+$+)#/ �2#(%+$+*(� �'3*27� ,'($+$7 #(, �*+)'1� ;� ;C �'�$'3&'2 ����I :� �9(,7 #(, �� �)8*6'2(� -:#2$+)+�#$+*(� �29$" #(, :#2$+#/+$7� :#2$+)+�#$*27 �)$+*( �'%'#2)"� �*339(+$7�&#%', �29$"�$'//+(0 #(, :*%$�)*(./+)$ �2#(%+$+*( +( �*2$"'2( 2'/#(,1 A����B =� ( �� � � C; ��� = �� H'#2(� -�+,+(0 ,'3*)2#)7J *(*2% #(, )+6+/ %*)+'$7 +( �*9$" �.2+)#1 A����B �; ����� ; ��� /� �;� ��I �� �*3'(� - *(*2 2+6'( �9%$+)' #(, +$ +%)*($'($%� �"' �#%' *. �4#(,#1 A����B �� '���� ����� ��� $��� � ��C !;�� � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/ �2+()+�/'% +(6*5', +( ,*3+(#($ 6'2%+*(% *. $2#(%+$+*(#/ ,+%)*92%'� $2#(%+$+*(� ,'3*)2#)7� #(, E9%$+)'� �"+2,� ,2#4+(0 �2',*3+(#($/7 *( +(%+0"$% .2*3 $"' .+'/, *. +($'2(#$+*(#/ ,'6'/*�3'($ %$9,+'%� $"' +,'*/*0+)#/ #%%93�$+*(% *. $2#(%+$+*(#/ +($'26'($+*(% #2' #(#/7%', +( $"' )*($'<$ *. # 4+,'2 -�*%$�)*(./+)$ #0'(,#1� �*92$"� $"' �#�'2 '<�/*2'% '6+,'()' %900'%$+(0 $"#$ # 3*6' $*4#2, # 02'#$'2 '3�"#%+% *( �#2$+)+�#$+*( +% '3'20+(0 +( $2#(%+$+*(#/ ,'&#$'%� �+.$"� $"' 2**$% *. �#2$+)+�#$*27 �2+()+�/'% +( 2#,+)#/ ,'6'/*�3'($ $"'*27 #(, $"' %$2'(0$"% #(, 4'#5('%%'% +( %9)" #( #��2*#)" #2' '<#3+(',� � )#9$+*9% (*$' +% 2#+%',� "*4'6'2� #&*9$ $"' )/#+3% $"#$ )#( &' 3#,' .*2 $"' �*$'($+#/ 3'2+$% *. # �#2$+)+�#$*27 #��2*#)"� �+(#//7� 9%+(0 # )#%' %$9,7 *. $"' �2,*7(' �*33'3*2#$+*( :2*E')$� # &*$$*3�9� -$29$"�$'//+(01 �2*E')$ +( �*2$"'2( 2'/#(, +( 4"+)" $"' #9$"*2% 4'2' +(6*/6',� $"' �#�'2 4+// ,+%)9%% #(, '<�/*2' $"' )*($2+&9$+*( *. 02#%%2**$% -$29$"�$'//+(01 �2*)'%%'% $* $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)'� � #(, 3#5' %*3' 0'('2#/ %900'%$+*(% #% $* "*4 $"'%' 3+0"$ &' $2#(%/#$', +($* 6#/9'% 9(,'2�+((+(0 $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' �2#)$+)'� �"' #+3 +% $"'2'.*2' $* 3#5' # �*%+$+6' )*($2+&9$+*( $* $"' ,'&#$' *( $"' .9$92' ,+2')$+*( *. $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' #(,� #$ # �2#)$+)#/ /'6'/� *. ,+%)9%%+*(% #(, �*/+)7 +(+$+#$+6'% *( -&*$$*3�9�1 #��2*#)"'%� �H� ����� �� � �� �� ����� � ���� ���� �� �2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' +% # .+'/, *. +(G9+27 #(, �2#)$+)' $"#$ +% )*()'2(', 4+$" -$"' 6#2+*9% E9,+)+#/ #(, (*(�E9,+)+#/ #��2*#)"'% $* ,'#/+(0 4+$" � � � $"' /'0#)7 *. "93#( 2+0"$% 6+*/#$+*(% +( %*)+'$+'% '3'20+(0 .2*3 )*(./+)$ #(,D*2 #( '2# *. #9$"*2+$#2+#( 29/'1� � �"'%' #��2*#)"'% +(6*/6' # -%'$ *. +($'2�2'/#$', �2+()+�/'% #(, �2*)'%%'%1 )'($2', #2*9(, $"' +3#0+(', 2*/' *. /#4 #(, /#4� 3#5+(0 -+( )*(%$+$9$+(0 $2#(%+$+*(1 $*4#2, # 2#(0' *. 0*#/% #(, '(,%� C �"'%' 0*#/% #(, '(,% )#( +()/9,'� #3*(0%$ *$"'2%� $"' 2'%$*2#$+*( *. $"' -29/' *. /#41I E9,+)+#/ 2'$2+&9$+*( ,'%+0(', $* )*9($'2 # )9/$92' *. +3�9(+$7I 2')*3�'(%' #(, $"' 2'%$*2#$+*( *. ,+0(+$7 $* 6+)$+3%I 2'.*23 *. +(%$+$9$+*(%I %*)+#/ #(, �*/+$+)#/ -2')*()+/+#$+*(1I -(#$+*(�&9+/,+(01 #(, $"' 2'�)*(%$+$9$+*( *. $"' �#%$ *( $"' &#%+% *. # -%"#2', (#22#$+6'1� "+/' *.$'( )*3�/+3'($#27� $"'%' 0*#/% )#( *.$'( &' +( $'(%+*( 4+$" '#)" *$"'2 #(, $"' 6#2+*9% 3'#(% '3�/*7', $* �92%9' $"'3 A4"'$"'2 +( $'23% *. 4#2 )2+3'% $2+#/%� $29$" )*33+%%+*(% *2 %*3' .*23 *. 2'�#2#$+*(B 3#7 �2+*2+$+F' %*3' #$ $"' '<�'(%' *. *$"'2%� (,'',� *(' *. $"' 5'7 G9'%$+*(% $"#$ ('',% $* &' '<�/*2', +% "*4 $* #6*+, $"' �*$'($+#/ �2*&/'3 *. ,'(7+(0 *2 /+3+$+(0 2'#/ '(0#0'3'($ #(, #0'()7 4+$" %9)" 3')"#(+%3% $* # �*�9/#$+*( $"#$ "#% &''( %9&E')$ $* 7'#2% ��C � �2,*7(' �*33'3*2#$+*( :2*E')$� !�� ���8 ��� )�� �� �� �� A����BI :� �9(,7 #(, �� �)8*6'2(� $ �� ����� <�� ��������� � ��� $ ������ 3�� � �� � A����B ; �!� � �'' K"$$��DD444�0%,2)�*20D0*D$*�+)�09+,'%DE9%$+)'D$2#(%+$+*(#/�E9%$+)'L� C ��8� �'+$'/� �������� ��� * ����� A����B ;�� � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/ *. 6+*/'($ )*(./+)$� �'6'2$"'/'%%� +( )"#2$+(0 $"' ,+..+)9/$ �#$" A#% �#2$"# �+(*4 �9$ +$B &'$4''( -$** 39)" 3'3*27 #(, $** 39)" .*20'$$+(01� $"'%' 6#2+*9% #��2*#)"'% #(, '(,% *. $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' %"#2' # )*33*( .'#$92' +( $"#$ $"'7 -,'�#2$ .2*3 ,*+(0 (*$"+(01 +( ,'#/+(0 4+$" $"' #.$'23#$" *. 3#%% 6+*/'()'� � �9$ 4"'(� 4"7� #(, "*4 "#% $"+% +,'# *. (* /*(0'2 -,*+(0 (*$"+(01 #&*9$ $"' /'0#)7 *. #$2*)+$7 #(, 4"*/'%#/' "93#( 2+0"$% 6+*/#$+*(% '3'20',J "+/' �*( �/%$'2 �'2%9#%+6'/7 #209'% $"#$ $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' )#( &' ,#$', &#)5 $* $"' &+2$" A+( )/#%%+)#/ �$"'(%B *. ,'3*)2#)7 +$%'/.� 3*,'2( )*()'�$+*(% *. $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' '3'20' 4+$" $"' )*()'2$', '..*2$% $* '(%"2+(' +($'2� (#$+*(#/ /#4 #$ $"' "'#2$ *. +($'2�%$#$' 2'/#$+*(% +( $"' 4#5' *. $"' �')*(, *2/, #2� ! �% �9$+ �'+$'/ #209'%� $"' "'7,#7 *. �*%$�4#2 $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' 4#% 3#25', &7 #( -'<)'�$+*(#/ #(, +($'2(#$+*(#/1 #��2*#)"� �"+% 4#% 3*%$ '6+,'($ +( $"' �2*/+.'2#$+*( *. 5'7 +($'2(#$+*(#/ $2'#$+'%� %9)" #% $"' 8'(*)+,' �*(6'($+*( A;!=�B� $"' �(+6'2%#/ ')/#2#$+*( *. H93#( �+0"$% A;!=�B� #(, $"' 8'('6# �*(6'($+*( *( �#4% *. #2 A;!=!B� #(, $"' '#2/7 #$$'3�$% $* +(%$+0#$' # 2'0+3' *. +($'2(#$+*(#/ )2+3+(#/ #))*9($#&+/+$7 +( $"' 4#2 $2+#/% "'/, +( �92'3&920 #(, �*57*� H*4'6'2� +$ 4#% *(/7 .*//*4+(0 $"' '(, *. $"' �*/, #2� ,2+6'( .+2%$ &7 (#$+*(�&9+/,+(0 �*/+$+)#/ $2#(%+$+*(%� $"'( &7 0/*&#/+F#$+*( #(, $"' 02*4+(0 +3�*2$#()' 0+6'( $* )*(./+)$ 2'%*/9$+*( %$2#$'0+'%� $"#$ -$2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' 3*6'% .2*3 $"' '<)'�$+*( $* $"' (*23 $* &')*3' # �#2#,+03 *. 29/' *. /#41� ;� ( %+3+/#2 6'+(� :2+%)+//# H#7('2 "#% "+0"/+0"$', $4* 5'7 .#)$*2% $"#$ "#6' %$+39/#$', $"+% 3*2' 2')'($ 02*4$" *. +($'2'%$ +( $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)'� �+2%$� $"' )+2)93%$#()'% *. $2#(%+$+*(#/ %*)+'$+'% $"'3%'/6'% #(,� %')*(,� $"' +()2'#%', �9&/+) +($'2'%$ #(, +($'2� (#$+*(#/ '<�')$#$+*( $"#$ #))*9($#&+/+$7 +% ,9' #.$'2 #$2*)+$7� ;; �"' 2'%9/$ "#% &''( # 02'#$'2 .*)9% *( $"' +%%9'% .#)+(0 %*)+'$+'% '3'20+(0 .2*3 6+*/'($ )*(./+)$ 9(,'2$#5'( &7 # 4+,' 2#(0' *. +($'2(#$+*(#/ #)$*2%� +()/9,+(0 2'0+*(#/ #(, (*(�0*6'2(3'($#/ *20#(+F#$+*(% A�8�%B� +($'2(#$+*(#/ .+(#(� )+#/ #(, *$"'2 +(%$+$9$+*(% #(,� *. )*92%'� $"' �(+$', �#$+*(%� ( $"+% �2*)'%%� /'0#/ $"'*2+'%� �2#)$+)'%� #(, +(%$+$9$+*(% "#6' )*3' $* &' 6+'4', #% +()2'#%+(0/7 )'($2#/ +( .#)+/+$#$+(0 #(, %"#�+(0 $2#(%+$+*(� *.$'( $"'3%'/6'% .2#3', &7 4"#$ #2' )*()'+6', #% -9(+6'2%#/1 )*()'�$+*(% *. E9%$+)'� �'2$#+(/7 $"' +($'2(#$+*(#/ )*339(+$7 A#(, %�')+.+)#//7 $"' �(+$', �#$+*(%B "#% +()2'#%+(0/7 '3&2#)', #(, '3�/*7', $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' ,+%)*92%'% #(, 3')"#(+%3% +( +$% +($'26'($+*(% +( -�*%$�)*(./+)$1 %+$9#$+*(%� ��� � �� �+(*4� +������ =�� ����� ��� 9 � �������8 9���� 2��� �� ����� >�� ���� ��� ?��� =� ����� A;!!�B =� ! �� �/%$'2� $� ��� ��� + ��8 �������� ��� * ����� �� 2��� ����� ���������� A���=BI ��8� �'+$'/� -�2#(%+$+*(#/ �9%$+)' 8'('#/*071 A����B ;� 2������ 2 ��� 3� ��� *� �! !=� ;� �'+$'/� +,�� �� C;� ;; :� H#7('2� -�9%$+)' +( �2#(%+$+*(� �"#//'(0'% #(, ���*2$9(+$+'%1� �2'%'($#$+*( $* ��$" �((9#/ : D�8� �*(.'2'()'� -�'&9+/,+(0 �*)+'$+'% �3'20+(0 .2*3 �*(./+)$� � �"#2', �'%�*(%+&+/+$71 A����B ; ;�� � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/ �"' �')2'$#27 8'('2#/ *. $"' �(+$', �#$+*(%� ?*.+ �((#(� +( "+% 2'�*2$ $* $"' �')92+$7 �*9()+/ +( �909%$ ���=� #)5(*4/',0', $"#$ $"'2' "#, &''( #( +()2'#%', .*)9% &7 $"' �(+$', �#$+*(% *( G9'%$+*(% *. E9%$+)'� $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)'� #(, $"' 29/' *. /#4 +( )*(./+)$ #(, �*%$�)*(./+)$ %*)+'$+'%� ;� H' (*$'% $"#$ ,+2')$ �� +(6*/6'3'($ +( �*%$�)*(./+)$ %*)+'$+'% "#% &''( )"#2#)$'2+F', &7 $"' +3�*2$#$+*( *. $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' #��#2#$9%� .*2 '<#3�/'� +( ?*%*6* #(, �+3*2��'%$'� 4"'2' $"' �� "#% &''( ,+2')$/7 +(6*/6', +( $"' #,3+(+� %$2#$+*( *. E9,+)+#2+'%� �*/+)'� #(, �2+%*( %'26+)'%� ( *$"'2 )*9($2+'% A%9)" #% �/ �#/6#,*2� 89#$'3#/#� �*$' ,1 6*+2'� �+&'2+#� #(, H#+$+B 5'7 29/' *. /#4 )*3�*('($% "#6' &''( ,'6+%', &7 �(+$', �#$+*(% -'<�'2$%1� ;� (,'',� +( "+% 2'�*2$� $"' �')2'$#27 8'('2#/ �2*6+,'% # ,'.+(+$+*( *. $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' $"#$ '3�"#%+F'% $"' '<�#(%+6' 2*/' '(6+%#0', .*2 $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' +,'#%� #��2*#)"'%� #(, 3*,'/%� ;= �(+$', �#$+*(% 29/' *. /#4 #(, $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' *�'2#$+*(% "#6' 4*25', $* %$2'(0$"'( ,*3'%$+) /#4 '(.*2)'3'($ #(, E9%$+)' +(%$+$9$+*(%� .#)+/+$#$' (#$+*(#/ )*(%9/$#$+*(% *( E9%$+)' 2'.*23� )**2,+(#$' +($'2(#$+*(#/ 29/' *. /#4 #%%+%$#()'� 3*(+$*2 #(, 2'�*2$ *( )*92$ �2*)'',+(0%� $2#+( (#$+*(#/ E9%$+)' %')$*2 *..+)+#/%� %9��*2$ /*)#/ E9,+)+#/ 2'.*23 &*,+'%� #(, #,6+%' "*%$�)*9($27 29/' *. /#4 +(%$+$9$+*(%� �"'7 "#6' #%%+%$', +( 6'$$+(0 #(, %'/')$+(0 (#$+*(#/ �*/+)'� E9,0'%� #(, �2*%')9$*2%� ,2#.$+(0 ('4 )*(� %$+$9$+*(%� 2'6+%+(0 /'0+%/#$+*(� ,'6'/*�+(0 *3&9,%3#( +(%$+$9$+*(% #(, "93#( 2+0"$% )*33+%%+*(%� &9+/,+(0 )2+3+(#/ ,'.'()' /#47'2%1 ('$4*25%� '%$#&/+%"+(0 /'0#/ #+,� #(, %'$$+(0 9� /'0#/ $2#+(+(0 +(%$+$9$'%� �*%$ (*$#&/7� 3+%%+*(% "#6' #%%+%$', "*%$ )*9($2+'% $* #,,2'%% �#%$ "93#( 2+0"$% #&9%'% &7 '%$#&/+%"+(0 $2+&9(#/%� $29$" #(, 2')*()+/+#$+*( 3')"#(+%3%� #(, 6+)$+3 2'�#2#$+*( �2*02#33'%� ;� ( 2')'($ 7'#2% $"' +(+$+#$+6'% "#6' '<�#(,', '6'( .92$"'2 $* +()/9,' 3'$"*,% .*2 2'+($'02#$+*( *. ,+%�/#)', )+6+/+#(% #(, 2'"#&+/+$#$+*( *. .*23'2 )*3&#$#($%I /'0#/ ',9)#$+*( $2#+(+(0 #(, %9��*2$ .*2 $"' *20#(+F#$+*( *. $"' /'0#/ )*339(+$7I /'0#/ #+,I +(,+0'(*9% #(, +(.*23#/ $2#,+$+*(% .*2 #,3+(+%$'2+(0 E9%$+)' *2 %'$$/+(0 ,+%�9$'% #(, .#)+/+$#$+(0 2')*()+/+#$+*(� ;� �* #%%+%$ +( $"+% '(,'#6*92� $2#(%+$+*(#/ )*,'%� 09+,'/+('%� #(, 29/' *. /#4 �*/+)7 $**/% "#6' &''( ,'6+%',� �"' �..+)' *. $"' �� H+0" �*33+%%+*('2 .*2 H93#( �+0"$% A�H�H�B 2')'($/7 2'/'#%', 3 ��� ����� � �� � � ��� ��! ;� �� �')2'$#27�8'('2#/� ��� � �� � ��� ��� �������� ��� � ����� �� � ������ ��� � ��� � ������ � ������� A���=B �� *)� �D���=D�;�� #$ =� ;� +,�� #$ ��� � �� ;= �2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' +% ,'.+(', #% )*3�2+%+(0 A+,�� #$ �� =B� $"' .9// 2#(0' *. �2*)'%%'% #(, 3')"#(+%3% #%%*)+#$', 4+$" # %*)+'$71% #$$'3�$% $* )*3' $* $'23% 4+$" # /'0#)7 *. /#20' %)#/' �#%$ #&9%'%� +( *2,'2 $* '(%92' #))*9($#&+/+$7� %'26' E9%$+)' #(, #)"+'6' 2')*()+/+#$+*(� �"'%' 3#7 +()/9,' &*$" E9,+)+#/ #(, (*(�E9,+)+#/ 3')"#(+%3%� 4+$" ,+..'2+(0 /'6'/% *. +($'2(#$+*(#/ +(6*/6'3'($ A*2 (*(' #$ #//B #(, +(,+6+,9#/ �2*%')9$+*(%� 2'�#2#$+*(%� $29$"� %''5+(0� +(%$+$9$+*(#/ 2'.*23� 6'$$+(0 #(, ,+%3+%%#/%� *2 # )*3&+(#$+*( $"'2'*.� ;� +,�� #$ ��� � �� ;� +,�� #$ �� ;�� � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/ � ������ (������ ;C �"'%' 09+,'/+('% #2' $"' .+2%$ +( # %'2+'% *. �9&/+%"', 3#$'2+#/% ,'%+0(', $* "'/� �(+$', �#$+*(% .+'/, 3+%%+*(% #(, #,3+(+%$2#$+*(% '3'20+(0 .2*3 )*(./+)$ $* '%$#&/+%" /#4 #(, $* #,,2'%% $29$" #(, 2')*(� )+/+#$+*( +%%9'%� �"' $**/% 4+// &' ,+%$2+&9$', $* �(+$', �#$+*(% 3+%%+*(% #2*9(, $"' 4*2/, #(, +()/9,' 3#$'2+#/% %9)" #% 09+,'%� 3#(9#/%� #(, "#(,� &**5% .*2 +(,+0'(*9% �'*�/'%� 3+(*2+$+'%� �2*.'%%+*(#/ 02*9�%� ',9)#$+*(#/ +(%$+$9$+*(%� #(, '6'( �#2#3+/+$#27 02*9�%� ( #,,+$+*(� $"' �(+$', �#$+*(% +% ,'6'/*�+(0 #( +($'2(#$+*(#/ 2*%$'2 *. -'<�'2$%1 4"* )#( &' ,2#4( 9�*( $* �2*6+,' #%%+%$#()' +( �*%$�)*(./+)$ )*9($2+'% $* '%$#&/+%" $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' �2*)'%%'%� 2'%$*2' %"#$$'2', E9%$+)' %7%$'3%� #(, 2'&9+/, $"' 29/' *. /#4� �7 .#2 $"' 3*%$ �*�9/#2 $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' 3')"#(+%3 "#% &''( $29$" )*33+%%+*(%� �+()' $"' '#2/7 ;!C�% $"'2' "#% &''( # �2*/+.'2#$+*( *. $29$" )*33+%%+*(% 6#27+(0 +( 2'3+$ #(, %$7/' +( )*9($2+'% #% ,+6'2%' #% �0#(,#� �20'($+(#� 89#$'3#/#� �*9$" �.2+)#� 8"#(#� �#%$ �+3*2� #(, �*2*))*� $* 3'($+*( &9$ # .'4� ;� �"' 2#$+*(#/' .*2 +(+$+#$+(0 $29$" )*33+%%+*(% %$'3% .2*3 # ,'%+2' 4+$"+( �*%$�)*(./+)$ %*)+'$7 $* 9()*6'2 -$"' $29$"1 #&*9$ �#%$ +(E9%$+)'% #(, 42*(0,*+(0 $"#$ +( 3#(7 )#%'% "#% &''( ,'/+&'2#$'/7 -%+/'()',1� �"+% +% *.$'(� &9$ (*$ #/4#7%� /+(5', $* #9$"*2+$#2+#( 2'0+3'% 4"'2' $"'2' "#% &''( # &2'#5,*4( +( $"' 29/' *. /#4 #(, 4"'2' "93#( 2+0"$% #&9%'% "#6' &''( )#22+', *9$ 4+$" +3�9(+$7� 8'('2#//7� $29$" )*33+%%+*(% #2' *..+)+#//7 %#()$+*(', �2*)'%%'% 9%9#//7 +(+$+#$', &7 #( +()*3+(0 ('4 2'0+3' %''5+(0 $* 3#5' # -.2'%" %$#2$1 #(, &2'#5 4+$" $"' �#%$� � 02*4+(0 (93&'2 *. )*33'($#$*2% #2' *. $"' *�+(+*( $"#$ ,2#4+(0 # /+(' 9(,'2 $"' �#%$ +% (*$ # 6+#&/' *�$+*( .*2 %9)" )*9($2+'% #(, #209' $"#$ $29$" )*33+%%+*(% )#( &2+(0 �*%+$+6' &'('.+$% +()/9,+(0 -)/*%92'1� -"'#/+(01� -2')*()+/+#$+*(1 #(, 3#7 #%%+%$ %*)+'$7 +( 0'('2#/ $* 3*6' .*24#2, &7 4*25+(0 $"2*90" # 6+*/'($ �#%$� �(,'2�+((+(0 $"+% +% $"' )'($2#/+$7 *. -0+6+(0 6*+)'1 *2 '(#&/+(0 6+)$+3% $* -$'// $"'+2 %$*271� )*9�/', 4+$" $"' �2#)$+)#/ +%%9' *. �2*6+,+(0 2'�#2#$+*(% .*2 6+)$+3% #(, # 2'%$*2#$+6' 2#$"'2 $"#( 2'$2+&9$+6' )*()'�$+*( *. E9%$+)'� ;! �"'2' #2' #/%* (93'2*9% )2+$+)+%3% *. $29$" )*33+%%+*(% (*$ /'#%$ $"#$ $"'7 2'*�'( */, 4*9(,% #(, 3#7 0'('2#$' .92$"'2 �*/#2+F#$+*(I -$"' $29$"1 ,'/+6'2', +% *.$'( �#2$+#/ #(, /+3+$',I $"'+2 -$*��,*4(1 (#$92' )#( 3#20+(� �C� ;C �H�H�� 3 ��� ����� � �� � � ���� ������ (����� A����B� ;� :� H#7('2� )���������� �� ���8 9���� ��� $������ � � �� �� $ ������ �� A����BI �� ?2+$F A',�B� �������� ��� * ������ 2 � 1��� �� '�� ������� 3��� � ���� 9 ���� 3� ����� � �� @ A;!!�B� ;! �"' /+$'2#$92' *( $"' �2*% #(, )*(% *. $29$" )*33+%%+*(% +% 6#%$I %''� .*2 '<#3�/'� �� �+00#2 A',�B� + ���� ��� ���8 ?���� ���� ��� ' �� * ����� ����� $���� $ ������ A����BI H#7('2� +,�I �� ?2+$F� - "'2' 4' #2' #(, "*4 4' 0*$ "'2'� �( �6'26+'4 *. '6'/*�3'($% +( $"' �'#2)" .*2 �9%$+)' #(, �')*()+/+#$+*(1 +( ��� 5� ��� � !� ��8 $ ��� ���� ��� ���� 9���� ��� 9 � ��� ',� ��H� H'(5+( A����BI �� �#(+� +�� �� 3����� �� �8 (����� * ����� �� ��� (��� � � ;�� A����BI �� �')2'$#27�8'('2#/� *�� )+$�� (� ;�I :� �'+/%� -�')*()+/+#$+*( +( 89#$'3#/#� $"' 2*/' *. +($'//+0'($ E9%$+)'1 A����B == 3��� ��� $���� �� �!I ���� +/%*(� ��� ������ � �� �� ��� 3�� �������� � �� ( �� !�����8 5� �������� ��� ���!�������� (���� A���;B� � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/ #/+F' 6+)$+3%� #(, $"'2' #2' *.$'( 9(�#/#$#&/' $2#,' *..% &'$4''( $29$" #(, E9%$+)' *( $"' *(' "#(, #(, %$#&+/+$7 #(, �2#03#$+) �*/+$+)% *( $"' *$"'2� �*2'*6'2� $"'7 $'(, $* "#6' # (#22*4 .*)9% ,4'//+(0 9�*( +(,+6+,9#/ 6+*/#� $+*(% 2'%9/$+(0 +( $"' '<)/9%+*( *. # 2#(0' *. %*)+*�')*(*3+) +(E9%$+)'%� �� �*2' 2')'($/7 #$$'($+*( "#% $'(,', $* .*)9% *( $"' )*339(+$7 ,+3'(%+*( *. )*(./+)$ #(, $"' )*(.+(', #(, ,'/+3+$', (#$92' *. /*)#/ *4('2%"+� #(, �#2$+)+�#$+*( +( -$*��,*4(1 �2*)'%%'%� ()2'#%+(0/7 �*/+)7 3#5'2%� #)#� ,'3+)%� #(, �2#)$+$+*('2% #2' G9'%$+*(+(0 $"' �2*&/'3#$+) (#$92' *. $"' -*('� %+F' .+$% #//1 #��2*#)" #(, #2' )*(%)+*9% *. $"' 6#/9' *. #(, ('', $* /+%$'( $* #(, "'', /*)#/ �'*�/' +( *2,'2 $* ,'6'/*� /*)#//7 *4(', �2*)'%%'%� �; �/'#2/7 $"'2' "#6' &''( 3#(7 +(%$#()'% 4"'2' -*..+)+#/ $29$"�$'//+(01 "#% &''( )2+$+)#/ +( -0+6+(0 6*+)'1 $* 6+)$+3%� 9('#2$"', �#%$ #&9%'%� &2*90"$ �'2�'$2#$*2% $* E9%$+)'� #(, �2*3*$', 2'#/ �2*02'%%+6' %*)+#/ )"#(0'� H*4� '6'2� $"'2' +% (*$ 9(+6'2%#/ #02''3'($ *( $"' 3'2+$% #(, *9$)*3'% *. %9)" �2*)'%%'%� �*2 '<#3�/'� 4"+/' 2')*0(+F+(0 +$% 3#(7 %$2'(0$"% #(, &'('.+$%� )2+$+)% *. #%�')$% *. $"' �*9$" �.2+)# �29$" #(, �')*()+/+#$+*( �*33+%%+*( "#6' +//9%$2#$', "*4 &*$" $"' �"2+%$+#(�+(%�+2', '$"*% *. -2')*()+/+#$+*(1 #(, $"#$ *. -2#+(&*4 (#$+*(�&9+/,+(01 �2')/9,', )'2$#+( $"+(0% &'+(0 %#+, &7 $"' 2'/#$+6'% *. 6+)$+3% #(, $"*%' 4"* "#, &''( $*2$92', &7 $"' #�#2$"'+, 2'0+3'� �#2$+)9/#2/7 +( $"' �9&/+) "'#2+(0%� �� �*3' "#6' #209', $"#$ $"+% /', $* # .*23 *. -%')*(,�*2,'2 $2#93#$+%#$+*(1� �2*&#&/7 ,*+(0 3*2' +(,+6+,9#/ "#23 $"#( 0**,� �� �"' 5'7 G9'%$+*( +%� "*4 )#( 3')"#(+%3% *. $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' #(, -$29$"�$'//+(01 &' .2#3', +( *2,'2 $* #6*+, %9)" #( *9$)*3' #(, '(%92'� +( 3*2' 0'('2#/ $'23%� $"#$ 2'#/ �*/+$+)#/ '(0#0'3'($ #(, #0'()7 +% (*$ ,'(+', $* # �*�9/#$+*( $"#$ "#% &''( %9&E')$ $* 7'#2% *. 6+*/'($ )*(./+)$ #(,D*2 #9$"*2+$#2+#(+%3J � )*339(+$7�&#%', #��2*#)" $* -$29$"�$'//+(01 +% 9(,'2%$**, +( $"+% #2$+)/' #% *(' +( 4"+)" ,')+%+*(�3#5+(0 *6'2 $"' ,'%+0(� 2'3+$� )*(,9)$� )"#2#)$'2� #(, *9$)*3'% *. $"' -$29$"�$'//+(01 �2*)'%% +% *20#(+F', +(� 4+$"� #(, &7 3'3&'2% *. # 0+6'( )*339(+$7� $ %"*9/, &' +(.*23', &7 2'%'#2)" 3'$"*,*/*07 �#2#,+03% .2*3 &*$" �#2$+)+�#$*27 #)$+*( 2'%'#2)" A:��B #(, )*//#&*2#$+6' *2#/ "+%$*27 3*,'/%� H*4'6'2� $"'*2+%$% #(, �2#)$+$+*('2% %"*9/, &' 3+(,.9/ $"#$ $"' 6+2$9'% *. %9)" #( #��2*#)" #2' 3#$)"', &7 �*$'($+#/ �2*&/'3%� �= $ +% +( $"+% )*($'<$ $"#$ #( #(#/7%+% *. $"' �C; �� �#(+� +,� �; �'$$%� *�� )+$�� (� �� �� �� H#3&'2� -�+0"$% #(, �'#%*(%� �"#//'(0'% .*2 �29$" �')*6'27 +( �*9$" �.2+)# #(, �*2$"'2( 2'/#(,1 A����B �� 9 ����� ��������� ��� 5�� *� ;�C= !=I +/%*(� *�� )+$�� (� ;!� �� �� �#( ,'2 #/$� �� �2#()"+� #(, 8� �$'6'(%� -�"' �*9$" �.2+)#( �29$" #(, �')*()+/+#$+*( �*33+%%+*(� --�#)'11� "+%$*2+)#/ )*3�2*3+%' #(, $2#(%+$+*(#/ ,'3*)2#)71 A����B �C ��������� ��� *� � ������ �� ��� 3����� �� ��; �C� �= :� �9(,7 #(, �� �)8*6'2(� -� �2*E#( H*2%'J �29%$ #(, �(+*(+%$ �$$+$9,'% $* �29$" �')*6'27 :2*)'%%'% +( �*2$"'2( 2'/#(,1 A���CB ��������� ��� *� � �������� ��� * ����� ,*+�;��;�!�D+E$ED+E3��!I �9(,7 #(, �)8*6'2(� *�� )+$� A����B� (� �I �9(,7 #(, �)8*6'2(� *�� )+$�� (� �� � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/ �*%%+&/' 2*/' *. )*339(+$7�&#%', -$29$"�$'//+(01 %"*9/, &' �/#)',� ( �'($2#/ #(, �*9$" �3'2+)#� �#2$+)+�#$*27 #)$+*( 2'%'#2)" �2*E')$% %9)" #% :"*$*�*+)' "#6' �2*6+,', #( *��*2$9(+$7 .*2 )*339(+$+'%� 02*9�%� #(, +(,+6+,9#/% $* )2'#$' # -�9&/+) $'%$+3*(71 *. $"'+2 '<�'2+'()'%� �� H'2' # -%$*27$'//+(01 �2*)'%% "#% "#, $4* 3#+( #+3%� �"' .+2%$ +% $* +(%$+0#$' #( #��2*�2+#$' -)*($'<$ .*2 02+'6+(01� �"' %')*(, +% $* #//*4 6+)$+3% *. %$#$' 6+*/'()' $* -)2'#$' # %"#2', %$*271 #2*9(, 6+*/'($ '6'($% $"#$ "#, �2'6+*9%/7 &''( -%+/'()',1� �� �9)" �2*E')$% "#6' )*3&+(', 4+$" 4+,'2 -$29$"�$'//+(01 +(+$+#$+6'% A%9)" #% $"' �"92)"�%�*(%*2', ��H� �'�*2$ #(, $"' %9&%'G9'($ %$#$'�%�*(%*2', 89#$'3#/#( H+%$*2+)#/ �/#2+.+)#$+*( �*33+%%+*(B #(, *$"'2 .*23% *. ������ �� 4*25� �C :'2"#�% $"' 3*%$ 4'//�2'0#2,', #(, )*3�2'"'(%+6' /*)#/+F', *2 )*3� 39(+$7 �*%$�)*(./+)$ E9%$+)'�3#5+(0 +(+$+#$+6' +% $"' -)9%$*3#27 )*92$%1 *. $"' >����� +( �4#(,#� �*2 3#(7� +$ "#% "#, # 2#(0' *. �*%+$+6' &'('.+$% #(, �2*6+,', 9%'.9/ /'%%*(% .*2 '/%'4"'2'� �� �"' ;!!= 0'(*)+,' /'.$ #( #��#� 2'($/7 +(%923*9($#&/' #(, ,'6#%$#$+(0 /'0#)7 +( +$% 4#5'� �"' %"''2 %)#/' *. 4"#$ "#, $#5'( �/#)'� 4+$" #2*9(, # 3+//+*( ,'#,� #(, $"' )*33+$3'($ $* #)"+'6' %*3' .*23 *. #))*9($#&+/+$7 +( 2'/#$+*( $* #// $"*%' +(6*/6', #% �'2�'$2#$*2% A4"+)" )*9/, #3*9($ $* #% 39)" #% # $"+2, *. $"' #,9/$ �*�9/#$+*(B �/#)', #( +3�*%%+&/' &92,'( *( $"' '%$#&/+%"', �4#(,#( E9,+)+#/ %7%$'3 #(, $"' ('4/7 +(%$+$9$', ($'2(#$+*(#/ �2+3+(#/ �2+&9(#/� �! $ 4#% 4+$"+( $"+% )*($'<$ $"#$ $"' >����� )*92$%� +(%�+2', &7 -$2#,+$+*(#/ ,+%�9$' 2'%*/9$+*( 3')"#(+%3%1� "#6' &''( %'$ 9�� �� �% +//+#3 �)"#&#% (*$'%� +( #$$'3�$+(0 $* *6'2$"2*4 -,')#,'% *. +3�9(+$71 4+$" # )*33+$3'($ $* -/'#6+(0 (* %'2+*9% )2+3' 9(�9(+%"',1� �4#(,# +% #,*�$+(0 # -6'27 ,')'($2#/+%', %7%$'3 *. E9%$+)' #,3+(+%$'2', &7 (*(��2*.'%%+*(#/% #$ $"' /*)#/ /'6'/1 $"#$ )*9/, -%$#(, #% #( '<#3�/' .*2 *$"'2% 4"* )/#+3� +( $"' �*%$� )*(./+)$ '(6+2*(3'($� $"#$ /#20'�%)#/' �2*%')9$+*( +% +3�*%%+&/'1� �; �'$� '6'( "'2'� )2+$+)+%3% 2'3#+(� H*4'6'2 &*/, $"+% '<�'2+3'($ +( 3#%% #))*9($� #&+/+$7 3#7 &'� $"'2' #2' )*()'2(% $"#$ �*�9/#2 �#2$+)+�#$+*( #(, $"' ('',% *. �C� �� ���� �75'%� -�)$+6+%$ :#2$+)+�#$*27 �'%'#2)" #3*(0 $"' �#7# *. 89#$'3#/#� )*(%$29)$+(0 3'#(+(0% .2*3 %+$9#$', 5(*4/',0'1 A;!!CB �� *� � ( ���� ��� �� C�� =�� �� ���� �75'%� -�2'#$+6' #2$% #(, �"*$*02#�"7 +( :#2$+)+�#$*27 �)$+*( �'%'#2)"1 +( 2���� � � !��� � 3�������8 ������������ ��� ��� ��� �������� ',%� :� �'#%*( #(, H� �2#,&927 A���;B ���� �C 8� 890'/&'20'2� ��� 3��� ���� 8 ������ ���� '��� ��� ��� 5���� !������ A;!!�BI :� H#7('2� )���������� �� ���8 $ ��� ���� (���� ���� � ��� !�� ���� A���;BI �')*6'27 *. H+%$*2+)#/ �'3*27 :2*E')$ A��H� B� > �������� "���� ! ���A8 ��� 4������� 3�� �� � ��� 2 ��� 3� ��� 4������ !����� ���� � > ������� A;!!!B� �� �'' .*2 '<#3�/'� � �)"#&#%� -8'(*)+,' �2+#/% #(, 8#)#)# �*92$%1 A����B � *� � ��������� ��� $������� * ����� �C! !�� �! +,� �� �� ?+25&7� -�4#(,#1% 8#)#)# �*92$%� � :2'/+3+(#27 �2+$+G9'1 A����B �� *� � !������ 5�� != ;;C� �; �)"#&#%� *�� )+$�� (� ��� �� �!�� � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/ 6+)$+3% #2' .#2 /'%% # �2+*2+$7 $"#( 3#7 .+2%$ #��'#2� �� :'2"#�% 3*2' 4*227+(0/7� +$ "#% &''( %900'%$', $"#$ '/+$' �*/+$+)#/ +($'2'%$% "#6' &''( -�'26#%+6' #$ '6'27 /'6'/ *. *�'2#$+*( *. �4#(,#1% $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' %7%$'31 2'%9/$+(0 +( # �2*)'%% ,'%+0(', $* -/'0+$+3#$' �9$%+ ,*3+(#()' M$"#$N "#% 9(,'23+(', E9%$+)'1� �� �$"'2% "#6' '<�2'%%', )*()'2( $"#$ $"+% 9%' *. >����� #% # 6'"+)/' $* )*(%*/+,#$' 0*6'2(3'($ �*4'2 #/%* 2'+(.*2)'% 9('G9#/ �*4'2 2'/#$+*(% #(, #))'($9#$'% $"' %+/'()+(0 *. $"' 3*%$ 69/('2#&/' +( %*)+'$7� �= "+/' $"'2' 3#7 $"'2'.*2' &' 39)" $"#$ )#( &' /'#2($ .2*3 $"' >����� 3*,'/� +( 4"#$ +% #( 9(G9'%$+*(#&/7 ,+..+)9/$ )*($'<$ +( 4"+)" $* '%$#&/+%" # ('4 2'0+3' *. 2+0"$% #(, �#2$+)+�#$+*(� $"' /'%%*(% +$ "*/,% .*2 02#%%2**$% #��2*#)"'% $* $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' 3#7 (*$ *(/7 &' $"' 2'%9/$ *. +$% #��#2'($ �*%+$+6' �*$'($+#/� &9$ *. +$% �2*&/'3% $**� ����� � �� �� ���� �� �*2 3#(7� 2')'($ 7'#2% "#6' %''( $"' +()2'#%', #��2*�2+#$+*( *. $"' /#(09#0' *. -"93#( 2+0"$%1 #(, -$2#(%+$+*(1 #% �#2$ *. #( '%%'($+#//7 9(+/#$'2#/+%$ 0/*&#/ �2*E')$ *. -,'3*)2#)7 �2*3*$+*(1� �"' ,*3+(#($ �#2#,+03 .*2 9(,'2� %$#(,+(0 ,'3*)2#$+F#$+*( 4+$"+( $"' +($'2(#$+*(#/ )*339(+$7 '3&2#)', $"' #%%93�$+*( $"#$ $"' 3*6' #4#7 .2*3 ,+)$#$*2+#/ 29/' A'6+,'($ +( 3#(7 �#2$% *. $"' 4*2/, +( $"' �#%$ �� 7'#2%B $#5'( #% $"' '%%'()' *. $2#(%+$+*(#/ %*)+'$+'%� +(6#2+#&/7 +(6*/6'% ,'3*)2#$+F#$+*(� -�2#(%+$+*(1� #% (*23#//7 )*()'+6', 4+$"+( $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' $"'*27� $'(,% $* +(6*/6' # �#2$+)9/#2 #(, /+3+$', )*()'�$+*( *. ,'3*)2#$+F#$+*( #(, ,'3*)2#)7 &#%', *( /+&'2#/ #(, '%%'($+#//7 '%$'2( .*239/#$+*(% *. ,'3*)2#)7� �*2'*6'2� $"' #%%93�$+*( $"#$ -$2#(%+$+*(1 +3�/+'% # 3*6' #4#7 .2*3 ,+)$#$*2%"+� #(, $* ,'3*)2#)7 +0(*2'% $"' �2*&/'3 $"#$ "93#( 2+0"$% #&9%'% 3#7 )*($+(9' $* $#5' �/#)' +( )+2)93%$#()'% 4"'2'� +( $"'*27 #$ /'#%$� $"' (*23% *. /+&'2#/ ,'3*)2#$+) #))*9($#&+/+$7 �2'6#+/� �� $ #/%* $"'2'.*2' �'23+$% # 2#,+)#/ )2+$+G9' *. +3�/+)+$ /+&'2#/ 6'2%+*(% *. $2#(%+$+*( $"#$ 3#7 *$"'24+%' %$2900/' $* ,'#/ 4+$" $"' %9&6'2%+*( *. $"' 29/' *. /#4� 9(,'2 $"' 09+%' *. /#4 +$%'/.� +( *%$'(%+&/7 /+&'2#/ ,'3*)2#$+) %$#$'%� �"' ,'.+(+$+*( *. E9%$+)' $** $'(,% $* &' (#22*4/7 )*()'+6', #(, /+3+$', $* $"' /'0#/ %�"'2'� �% H'7F'2 "#% (*$',� -E9%$+)' +% #,,2'%%', +( # %5'4',� �#2$+#/ #(, �+')'3'#/ 3#(('2� #% 39)" &7 �2#)$+$+*('2% #% &7 %)"*/#2%� #(, �C� �� ?+25&7� *�� )+$�� (� ��I �'$$%� *�� )+$�� (� �� �� �'$$%� +,�� #$ �� C=!� �= �*3'(� *�� )+$�� (� =I :� �6+(� - +..+)9/$ �"*+)'% +( $"' �'4 :*%$��*(./+)$ �0'(,#� $"' ($'2(#$+*(#/ �*339(+$7 +( �4#(,# #.$'2 $"' 8'(*)+,'1 A���;B �� ����� ; ��� /� ;CC ;�!� �� �� �'//� �� �#3�&'//� #(, �� �OP �*/#P+(� -�9%$+)' +%)*92%' +( �2#(%+$+*(1 A���=B ;� ( ���� ��� 5� �� (� ���� ��� ��I �� �OP �*/#P+( #(, �� �#3�&'//� -�"' :#2#,*< *. �2#(%+$+*( +( �*(./+)$', '3*)2#)+'%1 A����B �C 2 ��� 3� ��� /� ;C� �;�� � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/ $"' #$$'3�$ $* 3#227 �'#)' #(, E9%$+)' #.$'2 )*(./+)$ 2'3#+(% /#20'/7 +()*3� �/'$'�1 �� �#3# �#(+ #209'% $"#$ $"'2' #2' %'6'2' �"+/*%*�"+)#/ #(, )*()'�$9#/ %"*2$)*3+(0% $* $"' 4#7 E9%$+)' $'(,% $* &' 9(,'2%$**, &7 $2#(%+$+*(#/ �*/+)73#5'2% #(, �2#)$+$+*('2%� 4+$" %+0(+.+)#($ �2#)$+)#/ )*(%'G9'()'%� �#$+*(#/ #(, +($'2(#$+*(#/ -�'#)'�&9+/,'2%1� +$ +% %900'%$',� .#+/ $* 2')*0(+F' #(, 2'%�*(, $* $"' )*3�/'<+$+'% *. 2'%$*2+(0 $"' 39/$+�.#)'$', ,+3'(%+*(% *. E9%$+)' +( /*4�+()*3'� 4#2�$*2( %*)+'$+'%� �"' *6'22+,+(0 .*)9% *( 2',2'%%+(0 ,+2')$ +(E9%$+)'% #0#+(%$ +(,+6+,9#/% A+( $"' .*23 *. "93#( 2+0"$% #&9%'%� 4#2 )2+3'%� #(, )2+3'% #0#+(%$ "93#(+$7B $'(,% $* /'#6' $"' +(E9%$+)'% $"#$ )#9%', $"' )*(./+)$ 9($*9)"',� �#$"'2� �#(+ �2*�*%'% #( #/$'2(#$+6'� "*/+%$+)� #(, +($'02#$', #��2*#)" $* )*()'�$9#/+F+(0 E9%$+)' +( $2#(%+$+*(� 4+$" $"2'' ,+%$+()$� &9$ +($'22'/#$', ,+3'(%+*(%� /'0#/� 2')$+.+)#$*27� #(, ,+%$2+&9$+6'� �C "+/' $"' .+2%$ *. $"'%' +% )*()'2(', 4+$" $"' 2'%$*2#$+*( *. $"' 29/' *. /#4� #(, $"' %')*(, 4+$" ,+2')$ "93#( 2+0"$% #&9%'% %9..'2', &7 +(,+6+,9#/%� $"' $"+2, +% ,'%+0(', $* #,,2'%% %$29)$92#/ #(, %7%$'3#$+) +(E9%$+)'% 2'%9/$+(0 .2*3 �*/+$+)#/ #(, ')*(*3+) ,+%)2+3+(#$+*( #(, +('G9#/+$+'% *. 2'%*92)' ,+%$2+&9$+*(� �*2 �#(+� $"' .*)9% *( $"' 2')$+.+)#$*27� +( �#2$+)9/#2� )#( /'#, $* # ('0/')$ *. $"' *$"'2 ,+3'(%+*(% *. E9%$+)'� �"' �*+($ "'2' +% (*$ $* %900'%$ $"#$ "93#( 2+0"$% *2 ,'3*)2#)7 ,* (*$ 3#$$'2� �#$"'2� $"#$ $"' #0'(,# &'+(0 %'$ .*2 $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)'� #% +$ +% )922'($/7 )*(%$+$9$',� $'(,% $* 3#20+(#/+F' +%%9'%� G9'%$+*(%� #(, #��2*#)"'% $"#$ 3+0"$ '+$"'2 )"#//'(0' $"' .*23% #(, (*23% *. '%$'2( 0*6'2(#()'� *2 +3�/+)#$' ,*3+(#($ 0/*&#/ ')*(*3+) 2'/#$+*(% +( $"' )#9%'% *. )*(./+)$� 2#$"'2 $"#( +$% %*/9$+*(� �#20+(#/+F+(0 ')*(*3+) E9%$+)'� #% 4+$" $"' ,'%+2' $* ,'$'23+(' $"' .*23% #(, /+3+$% *. ,'3*)2#$+F#$+*(� 3+0"$ $"'( &' 9(,'2%$**, #% �#2$ #(, �#2)'/ *. # 4+,'2 -+,'*/*0+)#/ &#$$/'1� �� �"+% #/%*� *. )*92%'� 2#+%'% $"' '6'( $"*2(+'2 -9(+6'2%#/+%3 6%� 2'/#$+6+%31 ,'&#$' +( $"' )*(� )'�$9#/+F#$+*( *. "93#( 2+0"$% #(, E9%$+)'� $* %#7 (*$"+(0 *. $"#$ *6'2 %*6'2'+0($7 #(, $"' E9%$ &#%+% .*2 +($'2(#$+*(#/ +($'26'($+*(� �"'%' +%%9'% )#((*$ &' ,'#/$ 4+$" %9&%$#($+#//7 "'2'� H*4'6'2� 4"#$ )#( &' %#+, +% $"#$ $"' #$$'3�$ $* #��/7 6#/9'% 9(+.*23/7 #)2*%% )9/$92'% #(, %*)+'$+'%� 4"'2' $"' �*%%+&+/+$+'% .*2 �'*�/'% +( $"*%' %*)+'$+'% $* �#2$+)+�#$'� +(./9'()'� #(, +3�#)$ 9�*( $"#$ �2*)'%% #2' )*(.+(', #(, ,'/+3+$',� +% +( '%%'()' # ('0#$+*( *. $"*%' 6#/9'% &7 $"' 6'27 3'#(% *. $"'+2 %9��*%', +3�/'3'($#$+*(� :9$ #(*$"'2 4#7� $"' 6#/9'% #(, +,'#% +(.*23+(0 E9%$+)' 3#7 ('', $* &' #2$+)9/#$', 4+$"+( #(, &7 '#)" )*339(+$7� &#%', *( +$% %�')+.+) 2'#/+$+'% #(, ('',%� .*2 &*$" )*()'�$9#/ #(,� +(,'',� �2#)$+)#/ 2'#%*(%� ( $'23% *. $"' /#$$'2� .*2 '<#3�/'� #% �#(+ �*+($% *9$� �C= �� �� H'7F'2� - *3'(� #2 #(, :'#)'� �*&+/+F+(0 .*2 �')92+$7 #(, �9%$+)' +( $"' �;%$ �'($9271� �� ���� $"' #0 H#33#2%5E*/, �')$92'� �� �'�$'3&'2 ���=� ; =� #$ =� �C �#(+� *�� )+$�� (� ;!� �� H'#2(� *�� )+$�� (� =� �� ���� � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/ +. +,'#% #(, +(%$+$9$+*(% #&*9$ #% .9(,#3'($#/ #(, �'2%*(#/ # 6#/9' #% E9%$+)' #2' +3�*%', .2*3 *9$%+,' 4+$"*9$ #( +($'2(#/ 2'%*(#()'� $"'7 3#7 ./*9(,'2� (*$4+$"%$#(,+(0 $"'+2 #%%'2$+*( *. 9(+6'2%#/+$7� �! �"#$ (*(� '%$'2( %)"*/#2%� /+6+(0 #(, 4*25+(0 +( 2'%*92)'��**2 #(, 4#2� $*2( %*)+'$+'%� "#6' /+$$/' 6*+)' +( '%$'2( ,*3+(#$', #(, 0'('2#$', #)#� ,'3+) $"'*2+'% #(, ,'&#$'%� 3#7 +$%'/. &' %''( #% #( +(E9%$+)' +3�#)$+(0 9�*( $"' %$9,7 #(, �2#)$+)' *. $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' 3#5+(0� �"' (#22*4 .*)9% *( G9'%$+*(% *. /#4� '6+,'($ +( 39)" $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' $"'*27� )2'#$'% �2*&� /'3% .*2 9(,'2%$#(,+(0 $"' +%%9'% #$ %$#5' #(, $"' )*(%'G9'()'% *. $2#(%+$+*(#/ �2*)'%%'% &7 2'3*6+(0 $"'3 .2*3 # 4+,'2 %$29)$92#/ %*)+#/� �*/+$+)#/� #(, ')*(*3+) )*($'<$� �� � >� �8 �H� -:��������� �� �8�� �1J �"' �2*&/'3 *. # �*$'($+#/ -,'3*)2#$+) ,'.+)+$1 /+'% #$ $"' "'#2$ *. # )2+$+G9' *. "'0'3*(+) +($'2(#$+*(#/ #��2*#)"'% $* -,'3*)2#)7 �2*3*$+*(1 +( �*%$� )*(./+)$ %+$9#$+*(%� "#$ +% '%%'($+#//7 #$ +%%9' +% $"' G9'%$+*( *. #0'()7� *. 4"* '(0'(,'2% #(, )*($2*/% )"#(0'� 4+$"+( 4"#$ "#% &''( $'23', $"' -�*%$� )*(./+)$ #0'(,#1� =� �"+% 2#+%'% .9(,#3'($#/ G9'%$+*(% #&*9$ �*4'2 2'/#$+*(% #(, $"' /'0+$+3#$+*( *. ,*3+(#($ +($'2'%$%� �% #/2'#,7 (*$',� E9%$+)' "#% &')*3' # 5'7 .'#$92' *. +($'2(#$+*(#/ .*2'+0( �*/+)7 #(, )**�'2#$+*( #(, +% *(' *. $"' 3#+( 4#7% +( 4"+)" $"' +($'2(#$+*(#/ )*339(+$7 "#% )*3' $* '(0#0' 4+$" )*9($2+'% +( $"' /#$' ;!!�%� �"' -E9,+)+#/+F#$+*( *. +($'2(#$+*(#/ 2'/#$+*(%1 +% #��#2'($ +( # 4+,' 2#(0' *. +($'2(#$+*(#//7 ,2+6'( �'#)'� &9+/,+(0� 2')*()+/+#$+*(� ,'6'/*�3'($� ,'3*)2#$+F#$+*(� 0**, 0*6'2(#()'� (#$+*(�&9+/,+(0� #(, 29/' *. /#4 +(+$+#$+6'%� =; �"2*90" %9)" +($'26'($+*(%� +($'2(#$+*(#/ #)$*2% #2' 0'$$+(0 ,''�/7 +(6*/6', +( �*/+$+)#/ #(, %*)+#/ 3#$$'2% $"#$ $"'7 #6*+,', 9($+/ 2')'($/7� �"' �2*&/'3 #0#+(� #% (93'2*9% )*33'($#$*2% "#6' #209',� +% $"#$ %9)" +(+$+#$+6'% $'(, $* &' ,*(*2�,2+6'(� 2#$"'2 $"#( 2'%�*(%+6' $* $"' ('',% *2 4#($% *. �'*�/' $"'3%'/6'%� �2*3 $"' ;!!�% *(4#2,� # ('4 #��2*#)" $* �*%$�)*(./+)$ ,'6'/*�3'($ "#% '3'20', 4+$" #+,� �2+3#2+/7 .2*3 $"' �*2$" $* $"' �*9$"� &'+(0 6+'4', #% # $**/ *. �*/+$+)#/ '(0+(''2+(0� =� �"' %"+.$ $*4#2, �C� �! �#(+� *�� )+$�� (� ;!� �� =!� =� �"' $'23 -�*%$�)*(./+)$ #0'(,#1 2'.'2% +( $"+% �#�'2 $* $"' 3#(7 #(, 6#2+', �'#)'� &9+/,+(0� )*(./+)$�3#(#0'3'($� -0**, 0*6'2(#()'1� ,'3*)2#$+F#$+*(� #(, 29/' *. /#4 #(, E9%$+)' +($'26'($+*(% %�*(%*2', &7 $"' +($'2(#$+*(#/ )*339(+$7� =; H'#2(� *�� )+$�� (� =I �*3'( *�� )+$�� (� =I �6+(� *�� )+$�� (� �=� =� H'#2(� +,�I 8� ?(#9% #(, �� �#2$+(� ---�2#6#+/% *. $"' �92*�'#( �#E11 �'%%*(% .2*3 �*%(+# H'2F'0*6+(#1 A����B ;=A�B *� � '�� ����� �� C=I �*3'( +,�I � �*&+(%*(� � � ��� �������8 >� �������� �� )( ���������� �� ��� 2� �� �� A;!!�BI �#(+� *�� )+$�� (� ;!I �� :#2+%� - ($'2(#$+*(#/ :'#)'&9+/,+(0 #(, $"' --�+%%+*( �+6+/+%#$2+)'111 A����B �� 3��� � ��������� ��� (� ���� ��C ��I �� :90" A',�B� 3� ������� � � ;��� � �� ( ������� A����BI �6+(� +,� � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/ -"93#( 2+0"$%1 #(, -/'0#/ #(, E9,+)+#/ ,'6'/*�3'($1 �2*E')$% "#% &''( )'($2#/ $* $"+% �2*)'%%� �'2$#+(/7 $"'2' "#% &''( # �2*/+.'2#$+*( *. %9)" �2*02#33'%� �*2 '<#3�/'� #+, .2*3 $"' �20#(+%#$+*( .*2 �)*(*3+) �*�*�'2#$+*( #(, '6'/*�3'($ A��� B $* -$2#(%+$+*(#/1 )*9($2+'% .*2 /'0#/� E9,+)+#/ #(, "93#( 2+0"$% +(+$+#$+6'% 02'4 .2*3 /'%% $"#( ��Q������� +( ;!�� $* # %$#00'2+(0 ��Q��; 3+//+*( +( ����� =� �"' (93&'2 *. %9)" �2*E')$% +()2'#%', .2*3 *(' +( ;!�� $* ;���� +( ����� H*4'6'2� *. 'G9#/ %+0(+.+)#()' +% $"' (#$92' *. %9)" 4*25� �*2 3#(7 )2+$+)% $"'%' �2*E')$% #2' �2+3#2+/7 ,*(*2� ,2+6'(� �*2 '<#3�/'� +( �4#(,# $"' (93&'2 *. ��� �.9(,', /'0#/ #(, -E9,+)+#/ ,'6'/*�3'($1 #(, -"93#( 2+0"$%1 �2*E')$% 2*%' .2*3 F'2* $* �� ,92+(0 $"' ;!!�%� #$ #( '%$+3#$', )*%$ *. ��Q�� 3+//+*(� �'$� #% "#% #/2'#,7 &''( $*9)"', 9�*(� $"' '<$'($ $* 4"+)" %9)" 4*25 +3�#)$% *( $"' /+6'% *. *2,+(#27 �4#(,#(% +% '<$2'3'/7 /+3+$',� ( #(*$"'2 +(%$#()'� +( �+'22# �'*('� $"' #((9#/ &9,0'$ *. $"' ��')+#/ �2+&9(#/ "#% &''( )#/)9/#$', #$ *6'2 ��Q�� 3+//+*(� 4"+/' $"' (#$+*(#/ E9,+)+#/ +(.2#%$29)$92'� 4+$" *(/7 $4* E9,0'% #(, ;� /#47'2%� %$#(,% +( 29+(%� == �% #/2'#,7 (*$',� $"' 6#%$ 3#E*2+$7 *. )*9($2+'% '3'20+(0 .2*3 )*(./+)$% #2' �**2 #(, $"'2'.*2' "+0"/7 ,'�'(,'($ *( +($'2(#$+*(#/ .+(#()+#/ +(%$+$9$+*(% A � %B %9)" #% $"' *2/, �#(5 #(, $"' ($'2(#$+*(#/ �*('$#27 �9(, A ��B .*2 2')*(%$29)$+*( #+,� � % #)$ #% )#$#/7%$% #(, 09#2#($*2% .*2 &+/#$'2#/ ,*(*2%� �% # 2'%9/$� �**2'2 )*9($2+'% #2' ,'�'(,'($ *( A#(, *.$'( "#6' (* *�$+*( &9$ $* #02'' $*B %9)" +3�*%', )*(,+$+*(#/+$7� "+/'� +( $"'*27� $"'2' 3#7 &' �*%+$+6' �*/+$+)#/ *9$)*3'% *. %9)" #22#(0'3'($% +( �2#)$+)' $"' '<$'2(#/ /'6'2#0' 2'%9/$+(0 .2*3 )*(,+$+*(#/+$7 "#% �2*6*5', )*(%+,'2#&/' )2+$+)+%3� (,'',� %'6'2#/ )*33'($#$*2% "#6' #209', $"#$ $"' -920' $* '(0+(''21 '6+,'($ +( %9)" �*/+)+'% +% )*()'2(',� #$ # %$2#$'0+) /'6'/� $* 3#5' 4#7 .*2 $"' +($'02#$+*( *. 4#2�$*2( %*)+'$+'% +($* $"' 4*2/, ')*(*37� �6'( +( )*9($2+'% 4+$"*9$ ,'&+/+$#$+(0 )*(./+)$� $"' 2*/' *. #+, #(, +$% '..+)+'()7 +% ,+%�9$',� �6+( #209'% $"#$ $"' '$"+)#/ #(, %$2#$'0+) )"#/� /'(0'% '()*9($'2', +( �*%$�)*(./+)$ %+$9#$+*(% #2' #( '<$2'3' '<#3�/' *. $"*%' �*%', +( 2'/#$+*( $* ��� ,'6'/*�3'($ #+,� #(, $"' +,'*/*0+)#/ #(, *�'2#$+*(#/ .*9(,#$+*(% 9�*( 4"+)" +$ 2'%$%� =� �"' )*2' )2+$+G9' +% $"#$ %9)" %$2#$'0+'% �2*3*$' # �#$$'2( *. ,'6'/*�3'($ ,'$'23+(', &7 $"' ,*3+(#($ +,'*/*07 *. ('*�/+&'2#/ ')*(*3+) 3*,'2(+F#$+*( $"#$ +3&9'% $"' � %� ( *$"'2 4*2,%� 4+,'2 0'*��*/+$+)#/ #(, ')*(*3+) +($'2'%$% $** *.$'( %"#�' 4"#$ $'(, $* &' 2'�2'%'($', #% �*/+$+)#//7 #(, ')*(*3+)#//7 ('9$2#/ �*%$�)*(./+)$ #(, $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' +(+$+#$+6'%� �#2 .2*3 &'+(0 ('9$2#/� $')"(*)2#$+)� #(, �C� =� �*3'(� +,�� �� �!;� == +,� =� �''� .*2 '<#3�/'� �� �'209%*(� ��� !����� ������ ?������8 �'���� ������� '�� ���������� �� ��� + ��� ������ ��� �� 5�� �� A;!!=BI � *//#2 #(, � :2+$)"'$$� !������� !��8 ;��� ; ���� ;��� ' ����� ��� ;�� A;!!�BI �� �(,'2%*(� ' " 2���8 2 � !�� $�� ( �� �� ���� � ;�� A;!!!BI �� �+,,/'$*( #(, :� �1?''.'� '������� ��� '���� �����8 ��� ������ � 2 ���������� !�� A;!!�B� � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/ #��*/+$+)#/� #% �2*�*('($% 4*9/, )/#+3� +$ +% #209',� 2#$"'2� $"#$ $"'7 #2' ,+2')$', #$ 2')*(%$+$9$+(0 �*%$�)*(./+)$ %*)+'$+'% +( $"' +3#0' *. '%$'2( /+&'2#/ ,'3*)2#)+'%� '%$#&/+%"+(0 %9)" 3*,'/% #% $"' +,'#/ $7�' #(, %'$$+(0 '<$'2(#//7 ,'.+(', /+3+$% $* $"' .+'/, *. �'23+%%+&/' #)$+*(� =� (,'', $"+% "#% &''( /+5'(', $* # ('4 .*23 *. ('*�)*/*(+#/+%3� 2'%$+(0 9/$+3#$'/7 *( # $"'*27 #(, %7%$'3 *. %9&E90#$+*( 9(,'242+$$'( &7 # 2*3#($+)+F', 6+%+*( *. $"' '%$� "'/, &7 $"' '%$ +$%'/.� 4"* $"'( #/%* )*(%$+$9$' -$"' *$"'21 #% 2#)+#//7 #(, )9/$92#//7 +(.'2+*2� =C �"'2' +% # ,#(0'2 $"#$ $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' %$2#$'0+'% )#(� #% # )*(%'G9'()'� &' +3�/+)#$', +( $"+% �2*)'%%� �"+% +% )/'#2/7 )/*%'/7 $+', $* .9(,#3'($#/ )"#(0'% +( +($'2(#$+*(#/ 2'/#� $+*(% 2'6*/6+(0 #2*9(, # 2')*()'�$9#/+F#$+*( *. (*$+*(% *. (#$+*(#/ %*6'2'+0($7� =� �"' +($'2(#$+*(#/ 3+%%+*( +( �*%(+#�H'2F'0*6+(#� 2'0#2,', #% -0*6'2(3'($ &7 +($'2(#$+*(#/ '<�'2$%1 $"#$ (*$ *(/7 %"#�'% &9$ %'$% #(, +3�*%'% # �*/+$+)#/ #0'(,#� +% #( *&6+*9% )#%' +( �*+($� =! �� $2#(%+$+*(#/ #,3+(+%$2#$+*(% +( �/#)'% %9)" #% �#%$ �+3*2 #(, ?*%*6*� *.$'( 2'.'22', $* &7 $'23% %9)" #% -$29%$''%"+�1 *2 -�2*$')$*2#$'1� +(6*/6' /*)#//7 9(#))*9($� #&/' #0'()+'% +( ,2#4+(0 9� #(, +3�/'3'($+(0 /#4%� �� ( �.0"#(+%$#(� 2#G� #(, �+&'2+#� �2'.#&2+)#$', -E9%$+)' �#)5#0'%1 #2' %+3+/#2/7 &'+(0 2'#,+', .*2 +($2*,9)$+*(� �; �"'%' +()/9,' # 4+,' 2#(0' *. /'0#/ #)$+6+$+'% .*23'2/7 )*(%+,'2', $"' 2'3+$ *. (#$+*(#/ %$#$'%� �'$ $"+% 2+%' +( +($'26'($+*(+%3� &#%', *( '%$'2( )*()'�$+*(% *. E9%$+)'� "#% #/%* &''( �#2#//'/', &7 2'/9)$#()' *( $"' �#2$ *. 3#(7 29/' *. /#4 '<�'2$% $* #)5(*4/',0' $"' �*/+$+)#/ ,+3'(%+*(% *. %9)" #)$+6+$+'%� �<�2'%%+(0 $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' G9'%$+*(% #% # %'2+'% *. $')"(+)#/ +%%9'% *..%'$% $"+% �*$'($+#//7 $2*9&/+(0 2')*0(+$+*(� �� (,'', )2+$+)% "#6' #209', $"#$ $"' ('4 -�*%$�)*(./+)$ #0'(,#1 �*%'% ,''�� #(, 9(2'%*/6',� '$"+)#/ G9'%$+*(% .*2 ,*(*2% #(, *$"'2% $"#$ #2' %+3�/7 (*$ #)5(*4/',0', *2 #,,2'%%', +( $"' /+$'2#$92'� �� :��H �8 �� �:�� ���J ��� �8 �� �� :��� � :�� �� �*$4+$"%$#(,+(0 $"' )2+$+)+%3% ,+%)9%%', #&*6'� $"'2' ,*'% #��'#2 $* &' # 02*4+(0 2')*0(+$+*(� *( �#�'2 #$ /'#%$� 4+$"+( $"' +($'2(#$+*(#/ )*339(+$7 �CC =� ?(#9% #(, �#2$+(� *�� )+$�� (� =�I �6+(� *�� )+$�� (� �=� =C H'#2(� *�� )+$�� (� =I ?(#9% #(, �#2$+(� +,�I �*3'(� *�� )+$�� (� =I :#2+%� *�� )+$�� (� =�I �6+(� +,� =� �*3'(� +,�� �� �!�� =! ?(#9% #(, �#2$+(� *�� )+$�� (� =�� �� �� �'2,#/ #(, �� �#�/#(� -�"' :*/+$+)% *. ($'2(#$+*(#/ �,3+(+%$2#$+*(� ($2*,9)$+*(1 A���=B ;� >� ��� > ������� A��')+#/ %%9'B ; �� �; �*3'(� *�� )+$�� (� =� �� �!;� �� �� H924+$F #(, ?� �$9,,#2,� 3 �� � 5�� � ���� �� ���� 4������ ��� ($'2(#$+*(#/ :'#)' �)#,'37� 4*25+(0 �#�'2 A����B =� �� �*3'(� *�� )+$�� (� =� ��� �!� �I �6+(� *�� )+$�� (� =�� �� ;CC� � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/ $"#$ )*()'�$9#//7 #(, *�'2#$+*(#//7 $"' -E9%$+)' '($'2�2+%'1 ('',% 2'$"+(5+(0� �"9%� .*2 '<#3�/'� # ���� �� 2'�*2$ *( 0'(,'2� 'G9+$7� #(, �'#)' #02''� 3'($% '(,*2%'% # �#2$+)+�#$*27 #��2*#)"� �= �#+/92' $* '3&2#)' /*)#/%1 /+6', '<�'2+'()'% #(, *�+(+*(%� +$ +% #209',� )#( /'#, $* # �**2 9(,'2%$#(,+(0 *. �'#)' $2#(%.*23#$+*(� �"' #(%4'2� $"'2'.*2'� +% $* 6+'4 /*)#/ �'*�/' A+( $"+% +(%$#()'� 4*3'(B #% %$#5'"*/,'2% +(� #(, #)$+6' #0'($% *. )"#(0'� �"#$ /*)#/ *4('2%"+� *. )*(./+)$ $2#(%.*23#$+*( +% # -%'(%+$+6'1 #(, -*6'2/**5',1 +%%9' "#% #/%* 2')'($/7 &''( 2')*0(+F', +( $"' �� �')2'$#27�8'('2#/1% �'�*2$ *( $"' 3 �� � 5�� ��� �������� ��� * ������ ')27+(0 -*('�%+F'�.+$%�#// .*239/#% #(, $"' +3�*2$#$+*( *. .*2'+0( 3*,'/%1 *. $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)'� $"' 2'�*2$ #,6*)#$'% +(%$'#, #( #��2*#)" &#%', *( -(#$+*(#/ #%%'%%3'($%� (#$+*(#/ �#2$+)+�#$+*( #(, (#$+*(#/ ('',% #(, #%�+2#$+*(%1� �� (*23% #(, %$#(,#2,%� +$ %900'%$%� ('', $* &' 3#22+', $* -2'%�')$ #(, %9��*2$ M.*2N /*)#/ *4('2%"+�� /*)#/ /'#,'2%"+� #(, # /*)#/ )*(%$+$9'()7 .*2 2'.*23� �� �9)" *..+)+#/ �� 2'%�*(%'% "#6' .*//*4', *( .2*3 # 02*4+(0 )"*29% *. )2+$+)#/ 6*+)'% 2#+%+(0 )*()'2(% *6'2 $"' /#)5 *. /*)#/ *4('2%"+� +( $2#(%+$+*(#/ �2*)'%%'%� :90" +% )2+$+)#/ *. '<$'2(#/ #)$*2 3+%)*()'�$+*(%� "+0"/+0"$+(0 $"'+2 $'(,'()7 $* 6+'4 '($+2' �*%$�4#2 �*�9/#$+*(% '+$"'2 #% $2#93#$+F', 6+)$+3%� /#)5+(0 $"' #&+/+$7 $* 3#5' ,')+%+*(% #&*9$ $"' .9$92'� *2 #% �'*�/' ,2+6'( &7 # ,'%$29)$+6' �%7)"*%+% $"#$ 2'(,'2% $"'3 +()#�#&/' *2 3*2#//7 9(4*2$"7 *. �*%+$+6' )*($2+&9$+*(% $* �'#)'�&9+/,+(0� �� �"' -*$"'21 *. �'*�/'% +( 6+*/'($/7 ,+6+,', %*)+'$+'% #2' $"9% ,'(+', $"'+2 �*$'($+#/ )*($2+&9$+*( $* )*(./+)$ $2#(%.*23#$+*( +( ,*(*2 $"+(5+(0� �C ( %+3+/#2 6'+(� H924+$F #(, �$9,,#2, #209' $"#$ �2')/9,+(0 (#$+*(#/ *4('2%"+� *. /'0#/ 2'.*23� #(, $"' )*()'(� $2#$+*( *( )"#(0'% $* 2+0+, /'0#/ %$29)$92'% +% 9(/+5'/7 $* #%%+%$ %$#$'% #(, �*�9/#$+*(%� )2'#$+(0 # -�*$'($+#//7 '<�/*%+6'1 �2*&/'3� �� �% # (93&'2 *. )2+$+)% "#6' #/%* %900'%$',� +(+$+#$+6'% %9)" #% $"' ��� "#6' /#20'/7 .#+/', $* '(0'(,'2 /*)#/ '(0#0'3'($� �% # 2'%9/$� $"'7 $'(, $* 2'3#+( +(%$+$9$+*(% *.� +( #(, %''3+(0/7 .*2 $"' +($'2(#$+*(#/ )*339(+$7� 4+$" $"' ,'6'/*�3'($ *. +($'2(#$+*(#/ )2+3+(#/ /#4 �'2)'+6', #% $"'+2 )"+'. #+3� �)"*+(0 $"' �� 2'�*2$� H924+$F #(, �$9,,#2, )#9$+*( #0#+(%$ # 2*3#($+)� 9()*(,+$+*(#/ '(,*2%'3'($ *. +(,+0'(*9% %7%$'3% #(, %*/9$+*(% $"#$ 3+0"$ �'2�'$9#$' ,+%)2+3+(#$*27 �2#)$+)'% #0#+(%$ 69/('2#&/' 02*9�%� &9$ #$ $"' %#3' $+3' )#// .*2 +(.*23#/ 3')"#(+%3% 4+$" # 2'/'6#()' $* /*)#/ �*�9/#$+*(%� �C� �= �� �"+(5+(� -:'#)' �02''3'($% #% # �'#(% .*2 :2*3*$+(0 8'(,'2 �G9#/+$7 #(, �(%92+(0 :#2$+)+�#$+*( *. *3'(1 A����B ��� +6+%+*( .*2 $"' �,6#()'3'($ *. *3'(� �<�'2$ �''$+(0 *( :'#)' �02''3'($% #% # �'#(% .*2 :2*3*$+(0 8'(,'2 �G9#/+$7 #(, �(%92+(0 :#2$+)+�#$+*( *. *3'( � �2#3'4*25 *. �*,'/ :2*6+%+*( �8�D:����D����D�:�;� �� �� �')2'$#27�8'('2#/� *�� )+$�� (� ;� �� ;CI %''� #/%*� �� �')92+$7 �*9()+/ ����(, �''$+(0� �D:������I ($'2(#$+*(#/ :'#)' �)#,'37 A :�B� -�9/' *. �#4 :2*02#3% +( :'#)' ��'2#$+*(%� �*4#2, # �*(./+)$��'(%+$+6' :'2%�')$+6'1� )*()'�$ �#�'2 A���=B� �� :90"� *�� )+$�� (� =�� �� ;��� �C �� 8*2,*( #(, ��H �7/6'%$'2� - ')*(%$29)$+(0 '6'/*�3'($1� �+//#(*6# �(+6'2%+$7 �)"**/ *. �#4 4*25+(0 �#�'2 A���=B� �� H924+$F #(, �$9,,#2,� *�� )+$�� (� ��� �� =� � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/ �"'2' +%� $"'(� # 02*4+(0 #4#2'('%% $"#$ $"' �� #(, +($'2(#$+*(#/ #)$*2% ('', $* %'+F' $"' *��*2$9(+$7 *. ,'6'/*�+(0 # -%')*(, 0'('2#$+*( *. 29/' *. /#4 �*/+)+'%1� �! . $"+% +% %*� +$ +% �2+3#2+/7 &')#9%' $"' )2'#$+*( *. #( '(,92+(0 �'#)' %$+// %''3%� +( .#2 $** 3#(7 +(%$#()'%� #( '/9%+6' '(,� �6'2 =� �'2 )'($ *. �*%$�)*(./+)$ %*)+'$+'% 2'$92( $* )*(./+)$ 4+$"+( # %�#( *. .+6' 7'#2%� �� '%�+$' %9&%$#($+#/ +(6'%$3'($ +( $*��,*4( &/9'�2+($%� �2*E')$%� #(, 3')"#(+%3%� $"' 3*%$ )*33*( *9$)*3' *. # )+6+/ 4#2 +% #(*$"'2 4#2� (%$+$9$+*(#/+F+(0 #(, %9%$#+(+(0 �'#)'� +$ +% +()2'#%+(0/7 &'+(0 %900'%$',� 3#7 2'G9+2' �/#)+(0 +%%9'% *. *4('2%"+� #(, �#2$+)+�#$+*( #$ $"' )'($2' *. /*(0�$'23 �*%$�)*(./+)$ E9%$+)'� H*4'6'2� +. $"'2' +% (*4 # 02*4+(0 2"'$*2+)#/ 2')*0(+$+*( *. %9)" +%%9'%� "#% $"+% &''( $2#(%/#$', +($* $"' 2'#/+$7 *. �*/+)7 #(, �2#)$+)'J H'2' $"' '6+,'()' +% /'%% '#%7 $* .+(,� '%�+$' &'+(0 +,'($+.+', #% 5'7 +%%9'% +( +($'2(#$+*(#/ 2'�*2$% #(, ,'6'/*�3'($ )+2)/'% .*2 3#(7 7'#2%� $"' 6+2$9'% *. /*)#/ *4('2%"+�� '3�*4'23'($� #(, �#2$+)+�#$*27 #��2*#)"'% "#6' $'(,', *(/7 $* &' +3�/'3'($', +( # 6#09'� 4'#5� #(, #, "*) 3#(('2� �; $ %''3% $"#$ 3#(7 *. $"'%' #2093'($% "#6' (*$ &''( $2#(%/#$', #)2*%% +( # )*3�2'"'(%+6' 3#(('2 +($* $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' $"'*27 #(, �2#)$+)'� ����� �8 ����� � ��������:� :��� � :����� �::����H $ +% &'7*(, $"' %)*�' *. $"+% �#�'2 $* *..'2 # ,'.+(+$+6' #(%4'2 $* 4"#$ $"' �2+()+�/'% *. # &*$$*3�9�� �#2$+)+�#$*27 #��2*#)" /**5 /+5'� H*4'6'2� %*3'$"+(0 *. $"'+2 (#$92' 3+0"$ &' %5'$)"', *9$ &7 .+2%$ 0+6+(0 # &2+'. *6'26+'4 *. "*4 &*$$*3�9� #��2*#)"'% $* ,'6'/*�3'($ '3'20',� 4"#$ 5'7 )*()'�$% "#6' 9(,'242+$$'( $"+% �2*)'%%� #(, %*3' *. $"' �2*&/'3% #(, +%%9'% $"#$ "#6' #2+%'( 4+$" $"'+2 +3�/'3'($#$+*(� � �#2$+)+�#$*27 )*()'�$9#/ .2#3'4*25 #(, 3'$"*,*/*07 9(,'2�+((', $"' 4*25 *. $"' �2,*7(' �*33'3*2#$+*( :2*E')$ #(, +% ,+%)9%%', +( ,'$#+/ +( $"' )#%' %$9,7 &'/*4� �"' 2**$% *. 2#,+)#/� -&*$$*3�9�1 �#2$+)+�#$*27 #��2*#)"'% )#( &' $2#)', $* $"' %*)+#/ %$2900/'%� �*�9/#2 9(2'%$� #(, 02*4$" *. 02#%%2**$% 3*6'3'($% +( $"' �*9$" ,92+(0 $"' /#$' ;!��% #(, ;!C�%� �2*3 $"'+2 *2+0+(� $"'2'.*2'� �#2$+)+�#$*27 #��2*#)"'% "#6' .*23', �#2$ *. $"' )2+$+G9'� '3'20+(0 .2*3 $"' 9(,'2,'6'/*�', 4*2/,� *. $"' �'2)'+6', .#+/92' *. �*2$"�+(%�+2', #(, ,+2')$', )'($2#/+F',� $*��,*4( *2 -&/9'�2+($1 #��2*#)"'% $* ,'6'/*�3'($� �� �.$'( )/*%'/7 $+', $* -$"+2,�4*2/,1 (#$+*(#/ /+&'2#$+*( )#3�#+0(% #(, /'.$� �C! �! :�� *�� )+$�� (� ��� �� ;� �� �� �*&'55� -�*(.'2'()' �'�*2$1 +( !���� ���������� �8 ���� (�� ���� ?��� ����� �� ���$ ������ ( ������� B 9� � ���������� � � ( ��������� 5 ��� 4��������� ',%� ��H� �&(*R$"'2 #(, :�H� �/92+ A����B #$ ���� �; +,� �� �� ��"*..� -82#%%2**$% �20#(+%#$+*(% #(, �8�% +( �92#/ '6'/*�3'($� ���*2$9(+$+'% 4+$" +3+(+%"+(0 �$#$'% #(, �<�#(,+(0 �#25'$%1 A;!!�B �; ; ��� '���� ����� ��C ��� � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/ '3#()+�#$*27 %$2900/'%� $"'%' %$2#$'0+'%� ,'%+0(', %�')+.+)#//7 $* )"#//'(0' ,*3+(#($ �#2#,+03% *. 5(*4/',0' )*($2*/ #(, �2*,9)$+*(� 4'2' ,'6'/*�', &7 #)#,'3+)�#)$+6+%$% *�'2#$+(0 +( �*9$" �3'2+)#� �9&��#"#2#( �.2+)#� #(, $"' �%+#( %9&�)*($+('($� �� �*2 :#*/* �2'+2'� .*2 '<#3�/'� �*�9/#2 ',9)#$+*( �2*02#33'% 4'2' ,'%+0(', $* )2'#$' -)*(%)+'($+F#$+*(1� # )2+$+)#/ %$#$' *. )*(%)+*9%('%% 2**$', +( �*�9/#2 '<�'2+'()' #(, �'*�/'1% 5(*4/',0' *. $"'+2 *4( %$29)$92#/ )*(,+$+*(% *. *��2'%%+*(� �"+% 2'%$% 9�*( # .9(,#3'($#/ �"+/*%*�"+)#/ �2*�*%+$+*( $"#$� +( *2,'2 $* *6'2)*3' $"' 2'�2*,9)$+*( *. )*(,+$+*(% *. #/+'(#$+*( #(, *��2'%%+*(� +$ +% (')'%%#27 .*2 �'*�/' $* +,'($+.7 $"'%' $"'3%'/6'% #(, $"'( $* )*()'+6' *. )*//')$+6' #)$+*(%� &#%', *( $"#$ 5(*4/',0'� $* *6'2)*3' $"'3� �0'()7 +% $"'2'.*2' �/#)', #$ $"' )'($2' *. $"' �/#$.*23 *. )"#(0'� ( 3#(7 4#7% $"+% �#2#//'/% $"' )*()'�$+*( *. 5(*4/',0' #(, #)$+6+%3 '6+,'($ 4+$"+( 2#,+)#/ ,'3*)2#$+) $"'*27� �*2 '<#3�/'� ')"*+(0 # 82#3%)+#( �'2%�')$+6' *( $"' -�2#<+%1 *. $"' -*20#(+) +($'//')$9#/1� �(+%92 �#"3#( )*($'(,% $"#$ �#2$+)+�#$*27 #��2*#)"'% )*(%$+$9$' # �*/+$+)#/ �2#)$+)' )"#//'(0+(0 (*$ *(/7 $"' +,'# *. *��2'%%+*( $"2*90" $"' )*($2*/ *. 3#$'2+#/ �2*,9)$+*(� &9$ #/%* .*23% *. ,*3+(#$+*( 2'%9/$+(0 .2*3 )*($2*/ *6'2 $"' -3'#(% *. 5(*4/',0' �2*,9)$+*( M+()/9,+(0N $"' %*)+#/ �*4'2 $* ,'$'23+(' 4"#$ +% 6#/+, *2 9%'.9/ 5(*4/',0'1� �= $ 4#% +( $"+% 6'+( $"#$ �2/#(,# �#/% �*2,# ,'%)2+&', $"' #+3 *. :#2$+)+�#$*27 �)$+*( �'%'#2)" A:��B #% $"' /'0+$+3#$+*( *. �*�9/#2 5(*4/',0' #(, �9,, H#// %900'%$', A�C �� �*9)#9/$B $"#$ :�� +% ,'%+0(', $* -0#+( # �/#)' #$ $"' 5(*4/',0'�)2'#$+(0 $#&/'1 .*2 $"*%' 0'('2#//7 '<)/9,', .2*3 %9)" �2*)'%%'%� �� :#2$+)+�#$*27 #)$+*( )#( &' %933', 9� #% # �2*)'%% $"#$ .#)+/+$#$'% $"' �'23#('($ #&+/+$7 $* +,'($+.7 #(, #(#/7%' �2*&/'3%� .*239/#$' #(, �/#( %*/9$+*(%� 3*&+/+F' 2'%*92)'% #(, +3�/'3'($ $"'3� $* 0#+( )*($2*/ *6'2 $"' �2*)'%%'% $"#$ #..')$ �'*�/'%1 /+6'%� �"'%' 5'7 )*()'�$% *. �#2$+)+�#$+*(� '3�*4'23'($� #(, )*339(+$7� &#%', �2*)'%%'% &')#3' &9FF4*2,% +( $"' ;!C�% #(, ;!��% 4+$"+( +($'2� (#$+*(#/ ,'6'/*�3'($ )+2)/'%� �%%'($+#//7� �#2$+)+�#$+*( +% $"' 3'#(% $* '3�*4'23'($� $ )*()'2(% $"' #&+/+$7 *. /*)#/ �'*�/' $* ,'.+(' /*)#/ *&%$#)/'% *2 �2*&/'3%� )*()'�$9#/+F'� +(+$+#$'� ,'%+0(� #(, +3�/'3'($ �2*� 02#33'% $* #,,2'%% $"'%' �2*&/'3%� �"' #+3 +% .*2 /*)#/ #)$*2% $* &' '3�*4'2', +( *2,'2 .*2 $"'3 $* 0'('2#$' #(, -,*1 $"'+2 *4( -,'6'/*�3'($1 $"#$ 4+// $"'2'.*2' #/%* &' %9%$#+(#&/' #.$'2 .*2'+0( ,*(*2% /'#6'� �"' 5'7 '/'3'($ +% *4('2%"+� #(, )*($2*/� 4"* +% )*(%9/$',� 4"* 3#5'% ,')+%+*(%� +( 4"*%' +($'2'%$% #(, 4"7� �"' .9(,#3'($#/ )"#(0' %9)" #( #��2*#)" ��� �� �� �#/%��*2,# #(, ���� �#"3#( A',%�B� !��� � ��� D� ���� �8 +������ ��� ? � � �� ���� ��������� �� !��� � 3������� A;!!;BI :� �2'+2'� ��� ��� � � ��� 4�������� A;!C�B� �= ���� �#"3#(� � ����� (����'���� �����8 ����������� � ��������� �� !��� � 3�������8 ! * ���� ��� � 1&�������� A;!!�B ��� �� �� H#//� - +%" �"+% '2' # :*'3 *. :2#)$+)'% *. :#2$+)+�#$*27 �'%'#2)"1 +( �'#%*( #(, �2#,927� *�� )+$�� (� ��� �� ;C�� � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/ #,6*)#$'% +% $"'2'.*2' # -$2#(%.'2 *. �*4'21 .2*3 $"' ,*3+(#($� ,')+%+*(� 3#5+(0 �'*�/' #(, +(%$+$9$+*(% $* $"*%' 4"* #2' %9&*2,+(#$', ,92+(0 $"' �2*)'%%� �� �"' 3#(('2 +( 4"+)" # 0+6'( �2*)'%% +% +(+$+#$',� ,'%+0(',� )*(,9)$',� #(, ,+%%'3+(#$', +% +$%'/. +($'(,', $* .*23 �#2$ *. # 4+,'2 '3#()+�#$*27 �2*E')$ &7 )"#//'(0+(0 $"' 4#7 +( 4"+)" 5(*4/',0' +% )*(%$+$9$', #(, 6#/+,#$',� - '3*)2#$+F+(01 $"' �2*)'%% +% 93&+/+)#//7 $+', $* $"' -/'0+$+3#$+*(1 *. $"' 5(*4/',0' �2*,9)', A*2 �9&/+)/7 #+2',B &7 +$� �'#/ �#2$+)+�#$+*( "#% $"'2'.*2' $* +(6*/6' 4"#$ "#% &''( $'23', -)*�0'('2#$+6' ,+#/*09'1I 4"'2' /*)#/ �'*�/' (*$ *(/7 -#,6+%'1 *( $"' %"#�' #(, ,+2')$+*( *. $"' �2*)'%% &9$ 39%$ #/%* "#6' $"' *��*2$9(+$7 $* &' )*//#&*2#$+6'/7 +(6*/6', +( ,')+%+*(�3#5+(01� �C �*339(+$7 3'3&'2% %"*9/, (*$ *(/7 -#,6+%'1 *( $"' %"#�' #(, ,+2')$+*( *. $"' 2'%'#2)" &9$ 39%$ "#6' $"' *��*2$9(+$7 $* -#$ /'#%$1 )*//#&*2#$+6'/7 )*($2*/� $ 2'/+'% *( # )*()'�$+*( *. "93#( 2+0"$% �2*3*$+*( $"#$ 9(,'2%$#(,% )*($2*/ *6'2 ,')+%+*(�3#5+(0 #% +$%'/. 5'7 $* $"' #)"+'6'3'($ *. $"*%' 2+0"$%� �2� #% ?'((7 "#% 2')'($/7 #209',� $"' 2+0"$ $* �#2$+)+�#$' +( ,')+%+*(% 4"+)" #..')$ *('1% /+.' +% &*$" #( '/'3'($ *. "93#( ,+0(+$7 #(, $"' 5'7 $* '3�*4'23'($ $"' &#%+% *( 4"+)" )"#(0' )#( &' #)"+'6',� �% %9)"� +$ +% &*$" # 3'#(% $* $"' '(E*73'($ *. "93#( 2+0"$%� #(, # "93#( 2+0"$% 0*#/ +( +$%'/.� �� �9)" �'2%�')$+6'% "#6' 9(,*9&$',/7 +(./9'()', 2'%'#2)"'2% #(, #)$+6+%$% 4*25+(0 *( 2'/#$+6'/7 %3#//�%)#/' #(, )*339(+$7�*2+'($#$', $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' �2*E')$% +( 3#(7 6+*/'($/7 ,+6+,', %*)+'$+'%� �"+% "#% �'2"#�% &''( 3*%$ *&6+*9% +( �#2$% *. �#$+( �3'2+)#� �"#$ �#2$+)+�#$*27 $"'*27 "#% &''( %* )*()'2(', 4+$" �2*)'%%'% *. -)*//')$+6' 2'%'#2)"1� $"' -)2+$+)#/ 2')*6'27 *. "+%$*271� #(, $"' -,+..9%+*( *. M%9)"N 5(*4/',0'1 9(,*9&$',/7 �2*6', $* &' #( +(./9'()' *( $"' " ��� ?�� A�'6'2 �0#+(B #(, ������ �� +(+$+#$+6'% $"#$ 4'2' %9)" # 5'7 .'#$92' *. "93#( 2+0"$% $2#(%+$+*(#/ #)$+6+%3 $"2*90"*9$ $"' )*($+('($ +( $"' ;!��% #(, ;!!�%� �! �% ,+%)9%%', &'/*4� �#2$+)+�#$*27 $"'*27 9(,*9&$',/7 +(./9'()', $"' 4*25 *. $"' �2,*7(' �*33'3*2#$+*( :2*E')$ A��:B� #% ,+, $"' 89#$'3#/#( " ��� ?�� +(+$+#$+6'� C� "+/' /*)#/ 5(*4� ��; �� �� �"#3&'2%� -:#2#,+03 �"+.$% #(, $"' :2#)$+)' *. :#2$+)+�#$*27 �'%'#2)" #(, '6'/*�3'($1� (%$+$9$' *. '6'/*�3'($ �$9,+'% 4*25+(0 �#�'2 A;!!=B ;� �C ?� �'#2 #(, :� �,4#2,%� -�9+/,+(0 # '3*)2#$+) �'#2(+(0 �*339(+$7 +$"+( : �1 A;!!�B CA�B ������� 1� ���� � C ;�� �� ?� ?'((7� -�"' �+0"$ $* :#2$+)+�#$' +( ($'2(#$+*(#/ H93#( �+0"$% �+'/,4*251 A����B ($'2(#$+*(#/ H93#( �+0"$% �'$4*25 ;� �! �#/%��*2,# #(, �#"3#(� *�� )+$�� (� ��I %''� #/%*� 890'/&'20'2� *�� )+$�� (� �CI 8� 890'/&'20'2� -�*+)'% *. $"' �*+)'/'%% +( �'%$+3*(+#/ �+$'2#$92'1 :#2$ ; A;!!;B ;�A�B 5���� !������� ����������� ; ;��I :#2$ � ;�A=B 5���� !������� ����������� ; ;;�I ��H� � *�� )+$�� (� �C� C� ( ;!!! �*&'2$* �'�#F �*�'F� # 3'3&'2 *. $"' ���H �2*E')$� 6+%+$', �2,*7(' #(, 0#6' # $#/5 #% �#2$ *. $"' /#9()" #(, $*92 *. > �������8 " ��� ?��� ( �#7 ���� $"2'' 3'3&'2% *. $"' ��: )*33+$$'' $2#6'//', $* 89#$'3#/#� 3'$ 4+$" #(, +($'2� 6+'4', #)$+6+%$% #(, +(,+6+,9#/% +(6*/6', +( $"' H+%$*2+)#/ �/#2+.+)#$+*( �*33+%%+*( A��HB� ���H �2*E')$� #(, �'($2' .*2 H93#( �+0"$% �'0#/ �)$+*(� �"' ��: )*33+$$'' %'2+*9%/7 )*(%+,'2', #,*�$+(0 $"' �'6'2 �0#+( $+$/' .*2 $"' &**5 +$ � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/ /',0' #(, '<�'2+'()' 4'2' $"' .*9(,#$+*( 9�*( 4"+)" $"' �2*E')$ �2*)'',',� +(%+0"$% .2*3 $"' %*2$ *. $"'*2'$+)#/ �'2%�')$+6'% *9$/+(', #&*6'� #(, +(%�+2#$+*( *. #)$+6+%$% +( �/#)'% #% ,+%$#($ #% 89#$'3#/# "'/�', %"#�' #(, %9%$#+( $"' 4*25� . $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' )#( /'#2( .2*3 $"' �#2$+)+�#$*27 ,+%)*92%' #(, $"'*27 $"'( +$ #/%* 3#7 ('', $* ,* %* .2*3 #%�')$% *. '<�'2+'()' +( $"' ,'6'/*�3'($ .+'/,I +( �#2$+)9/#2� $"' �*$'($+#/ �2*&/'3 *. )*�*�$+*(� �*2 '<#3�/'� 4"#$� '6'2 +$% 2#,+)#/ 9(,'2�+((+(0%� &*$$*3�9� *2 �#2$+)+�#$*27 ,+%)*92%' &'0#( $* &' '3&2#)', &7 3#+(%$2'#3 ,'6'/*�3'($ #0'()+'%� #(, #,*�$', &7 +(%$+$9$+*(% +()/9,+(0 $"' *2/, �#(5� C; $ +% (*4 # )*33*(�/#)' +( $"' .+'/, *. 3#+(%$2'#3 ,'6'/*�3'($ $"'*27 #(, �2#)$+)' #(, +% 2'0#2,', #% #( '%%'($+#/ +( 0**, �2#)$+)'� �"+% -%"+.$1 )#3' #&*9$ ,9' $* $"' ,+%#��*+($3'($ 4+$" #(, 2'#/+F#$+*( *. $"' -.#+/',1 $*��,*4( ,'6'/*�3'($ *2$"*,*<7� C� H*4'6'2� $"' #��#2'($/7 �*%+$+6' 3*6' $*4#2, $"' #,*�$+*( *. �#2$+)+� �#$*27 #��2*#)"'% +( 3#+(%$2'#3 ,'6'/*�3'($ +( 0'('2#/ "#% &''( %9&E')$ $* %'6'2' )2+$+)+%3� C� ($'2(#$+*(#/ +(%$+$9$+*(%� +$ +% #209',� $'(, $* '(0#0' +( # �2*&/'3#$+) )*�*�$+*( *. )+6+/ %*)+'$7 #(, #��2*�2+#$' �#2$+)+�#$*27 ,+%� )*92%'� �"' 3*6' $*4#2,% �#2$+)+�#$+*( %$2#$'0+'% &7 $"' *2/, �#(5 "#% &''( %''( #% # �*/+$+)#/ 3*6' $* ('9$2#/+F' 2'%+%$#()' $* �$29)$92#/ �,E9%$� 3'($ :*/+)+'%� %9)" # .'#$92' *. ('*�/+&'2#/ ')*(*3+) �"+/*%*�"7� ( 3#(7 9(,'2,'6'/*�', )*9($2+'% $"+% "#% +(6*/6', ,2#%$+) 2',9)$+*(% +( '<�'(,+$92' *( %*)+#/ 4'/.#2' �2*6+%+*( #(, %'26+)'% +( .#6*92 *. $"' �2+6#$' %')$*2� 4+$" ,'6#%$#$+(0 )*(%'G9'()'% .*2 $"' 3*%$ 69/('2#&/' 02*9�% +( %*)+'$7� C= �(' )2+$+) "#% �*+($', $* $"' 4#7 +( 4"+)" +($'2(#$+*(#/ ,*(*2% "#6' &''( %9))'%%.9/ +( +(./9'()+(0 $"' )922'($ 6'2%+*( *. )+6+/ %*)+'$7 +( # (93&'2 *. �.2+)#( )*9($2+'% A.*2 '<#3�/'� 8"#(#� �*9$" �.2+)#� #(, �0#(,#B� ( %9)" %+$9#$+*(% # 6*)#/� 4'//�.9(,', %')$+*( *. )+6+/ %*)+'$7� +$ +% %900'%$',� +($'26'('% *( 5'7 +%%9'% *. (#$+*(#/ ,'6'/*�3'($ %$2#$'07 #(, #)$% (*$ #% # .*2)' .*2 )"#//'(0+(0 $"' %$#$9% G9*� &9$ .*2 &9+/,+(0 %*)+'$#/ )*(%'(%9% +( +$% 3#+($'(#()'� C� �$"'2% "#6' #209', $"#$ ,*(*2% *.$'( &7�#%% 02#%%�2**$% �8�% +( .#6*92 *. -�2*.'%%+*(#/+F',1 �8�%� 9%9#//7 .*9(, +( 92&#( )'($2'% #(, )#�+$#/ )+$+'%� H93#( 2+0"$% #)$+6+%$% +( �+2 �#(5# "#6' 2'.'22', ,+%�#2#0+(0/7 $* %9)" �8�% #% -02#($ '#$'2%1 #(, %900'%$ $"#$ $"'7 2'�2'%'($ # "+0"/7 �2*.'%%+*(#/+F', -�'#)' +(,9%$271 $"#$ 2'%�*(,% $* ,*(*2 #0'(,#%� C� ��� �2*,9)',� �"' �2,*7(' &**5 +% %+3+/#2 +( %$7/'� .*)9% #(, )*($'($ $* $"' " ��� ?�� A�'6'2 �0#+(SB �9&/+)#$+*(%� C; *2/, �#(5� ��� ; ��� +��� ���������� � ( ���� � A;!!�B� C� �� �#"3#(� -:#2$+)+�#$*27 �)$+*( �'%'#2)"� �"' �#%$ �'3�$#$+*( *. �#+($ '6'/*�3'($1 A;!!�B ;� !����������� ;!! ���� C� �� H'#2(� -�"' --�%'% #(, �&9%'%11 *. �+6+/ �*)+'$7 +( �.2+)#1 A���;B �� 3��� � !������ ������� 1� � �� =� ��� C= �#(+� *�� )+$�� (� ;!� ��� ;�� ��� C� H'#2(� *�� )+$�� (� =� C� �� H#(+..#� - ( :92%9+$ *. '3*)2#)7 +( :*%$ �*/*(+#/ �2+ �#(5#� �*)#/ H93#( �+0"$% ���2*#)"'% $* �2#(%+$+*(#/ �9%$+)'1� )*�7 *. �#�'2 4+$" #9$"*2% A����B ��� � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/ �"+%� $"'7 #209'� 2'%9/$% +( %)#2)' 2'%*92)'% &'+(0 ,+6'2$', #4#7 .2*3 4*2$"7 "*3'�02*4(� &*$$*3�9� �2*E')$% $"#$ #2' )*(%+,'2', +3�*2$#($ &7 /*)#/ *20#(+F#$+*(%� �'�*2$+(0 *( $"' %+$9#$+*( +( �*%(+#� *(' 3#E*2 2'�*2$ *( )+6+/ %*)+'$7 &9+/,+(0 #209', $"#$ $"' %#3' ;������ �2*.'%%+*(#/+F', -'/+$'1 �8�%� 2'3*6', .2*3 $"' -02#%%2**$%1 �2*&/'3% #(, %*)+#/ 2'#/+$7� �2*,9)' #(, #$$'(, "9(,2',% *. 2*9(, $#&/'% #(, 4*25%"*�%� �% # 2'%9/$� *(' 2')'+6'% # .+)$+$+*9% 6+'4 *. /*)#/ �#2$+)+�#$+*(� 4"+)" 2'%9/$% +( 4"#$ +% ,'%)2+&', #% # -6+2$9#/ )+6+/ %*)+'$71� CC �"' %#3' 2'�*2$ 0*'% *( $* %#7� -+$ +% # G9'%$+*( 4"'$"'2 $"'%' M�8�%N 2'�2'%'($ #(7*(' '/%' +( #,,+$+*( $* $"*%' 4"* 4*25 +( $"'31� C� �"' /'0+$+3#)7 #(, )2',+&+/+$7 *. %9)" �8�% #(, $"' 9(+($'(,', 2'%9/$% *. 3#20+(#/+F+(0 �9&/+) �#2$+)+�#$+*( #2' %'2+*9% +%%9'% $"#$ ,*(*2% ('', $* 2'./')$ *(� �'2$#+(/7 %9)" )2+$+G9'% "#6' 2#+%', G9'%$+*(% #&*9$ $"' #)$9#/ 3'#(+(0 *. -�#2$+)+�#$+*(1 #(, -'3�*4'23'($1 #% )*()'�$% 4"'( #��/+', +( %9)" )+2)93%$#()'%� $ +% )29)+#/ $"#$ #,6*)#$'% *. �#2$+)+�#$*27 #��2*#)"'% 4+$"+( $"' .+'/, *. $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' ,+2')$/7 #,,2'%% #(, %''5 $* *6'2)*3' %9)" +%%9'% +( $"' ,'6'/*�3'($ #(, ,'%+0( *. %9)" %$2#$'0+'%� �"'2' +% #/%* # %9&%$#($+#/ &*,7 *. /+$'2#$92' +( ,'6'/*�3'($ %$9,+'% $"#$ )#9$+*(% #0#+(%$ 2*3#($+)+F+(0 �#2$+)+�#$*27 #��2*#)"'% #(, ,2#4% #$$'($+*( $* �*$'($+#/ #&9%'% #(, 4"#$ $"'7 3+0"$ )*()'#/� C! "+/' �#2$+)+�#$+*( "#% $"' �*$'($+#/ $* )"#//'(0' �#$$'2(% *. ,*3+(#()'� +$ 3#7 #/%* &' $"' 3'#(% $"2*90" 4"+)" '<+%$+(0 �*4'2 2'/#$+*(% #2' '($2'()"', #(, 2'�2*,9)',� �� �*2 '<#3�/'� 4"* #2' $"' -/*)#/%1 4"*%' 6*+)'% ('', $* &' "'#2, #(, "'',', #(, "*4 ,*'% # /*)#//7�'3�*4'2+(0 �2*)'%% *6'2)*3' "+'2#2)"#/ ,+..'2'()'% A.*2 '<#3�/'� *. 0'(,'2B 4+$"+( # /*)#/ )*339(+$7 $"#$ )#( *$"'24+%' �2')/9,' 0+6+(0 #0'()7 $* $"' 3*%$ 3#20+(#/+F',J �; �% �*"#( "#% #209', $"' 2"'$*2+) *. �#2$+)+�#$+*( *.$'( %'26'% $* )*()'#/ $"' *�'2#$+*( *. �*4'2.9/ +($'2'%$% ������ )*339(+$+'%� �� �9)" )2+$+)+%3% 2#+%' +3�*2$#($ �*+($% #&*9$ $"' +3�#)$ *. +($'2(#$+*(#/ #+, #(, +($'26'($+*( +( 0'('2#/ #(, $"' ,'&#$' #&*9$ 4"* &'#2% $"' )*%$ *. '22*2� ��� CC TU� :#�+)P� -�"' 8'('2#/ �+$9#$+*( +( �*%(+#�H'2F'0*6+(# #(, ($'2(#$+*(#/ �9��*2$ :*/+)+'%1 A���;B +( ��������� ��� ( �� �� ������ � ( �� 1��� 1 � ���� $ ������ B 5��� �� #" �% 5������ �� + �����2���� ���� ',� TU� :#�+)P A���;B ;�� C� �� �#/+��'2F+)� -�+6+/ �*)+'$71 +( :#�+)P A',�B� +,�� �� ;��� C! �� 8#6'($#� -:#2$+)+�#$*27 '6'/*�3'($ *2 :#2$+)+�#$*27 '3*)2#)7J �+(5+(0 :#2$+)+�#$*27 ���2*#)"'% $* :*/+)7 #(, 8*6'2(#()'1 A���=B (*� �� ��������� �� 5������ ��� !��� � ;�� !I �� "+$'� - '�*/+$+)+%+(0 '6'/*�3'($� �"' �%'% #(, �&9%'% *. :#2$+)+�#$+*(1 A;!!�B � '���� ����� �� ������� � ;�I (%$+$9$' *. '6'/*�3'($ �$9,+'% A �B� :#2$+)+�#$+*( 82*9�� K444�+,%�#)�95D+,%D�#2$+)+�L� �� "+$'� +,�� �� �� �; �*&'55� *�� )+$�� (� ��� �� ��=� �� 8� �*"#(� -�*$ %* +%$#($� �*$ %* �$2#(0'� $"' :'2%*(#/ #(, $"' :*/+$+)#/ +( :#2$+)+�#$*27 �'%'#2)"1 A;!!!B � 1������ ���� ��� ��� 1���� ����� =; �=� #$ =�� � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/ �H� �� ���� ���������� �� :������� � ���� ��� � �� ��������: ����� � ���� ���� �� ;� ��� � ���&�� ���� � � �� ��� ��� �� � ��� �� ���� �"'%' )2+$+G9'% *. �#2$+)+�#$*27 #��2*#)"'% $* ,'6'/*�3'($� �*%$�)*(./+)$ $2#(%+$+*(� #(, E9%$+)'�3#5+(0 #2' )/'#2/7 %+0(+.+)#($ #(, %"*9/, +(.*23 �*/+)7 3#5+(0 #(, �2#)$+)'� �'6'2$"'/'%%� 0+6'( $"' #��#2'($ +%%9'% #/2'#,7 '<#3+(', $"#$ #2+%' .2*3 -$*��,*4(1 3')"#(+%3%� $"'2' %$+// #��'#2% $* &' # �2'%%+(0 ('', .*2 $"' )2'#$+*( *. 0'(9+(' ,+#/*09' #(, 02#%%2**$% *4('2%"+� *. $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' �2*)'%%'% $"#$ 4+// #//*4 /*)#/ �'*�/' $* &' /+%$'(', $* #(, "'',',� �"' #,*�$+*( *. &*$$*3�9� #��2*#)"'% ,'%+0(', $* '()*92#0' �#2$+)+�#$+*( #(, �*%+$+6' %*)+#/ )"#(0' +% ,+2')$', $* �2')+%'/7 $"+% '(,� ( *2,'2 $* +//9%$2#$' $"' �*$'($+#/ 6#/9'% A#(, /+3+$#$+*(%B *. %9)" �'2%�')$+6'% #(, �2#)$+)'% 4' 4+// (*4 .*)9% *( #( '<#3�/' *. #( +(+$+#$+6' 4+$" 4"+)" $"' #9$"*2% 4'2' )/*%'/7 +(6*/6', +( �*2$"'2( 2'/#(,� �"+% 4#% $"' �2,*7(' �*33'3*2#$+*( :2*E')$ A��:B� �� �"' ��: 4#% # 02#%%2**$% -%+(0/' +,'($+$7 $29$" 2')*6'271 �2*E')$ %'$ 9� +( $"' �2,*7(' #2'# *. �*2$" �'/.#%$� �2,*7(' +% # %3#//� �#$"*/+)� 4*25+(0� )/#%%� 2'�9&/+)#( )*339(+$7 4+$" # �*�9/#$+*( *. #��2*<+3#$'/7 C����� $ +% #( '()/#6' #2'#� %922*9(,', *( $"2'' %+,'% &7 ('+0"&*2+(0 :2*$'%$#($ 4*25+(0�)/#%% )*339(+$+'%� 4+$" 4"+)" +$ %"#2'% # %'2+'% *. -+($'2.#)'%1� �% # 4"*/'� �*2$" �'/.#%$ 4#% $"' %+$' .*2 2*90"/7 �� �'2 )'($ *. #// )*(./+)$� 2'/#$', ,'#$"% #(, &'$4''( ;!�! #(, ;!!�� !! �'*�/' .2*3 �2,*7(' 4'2' 5+//', &7 $"' 6#2+*9% �#2$+'% $* $"' )*(./+)$� *(' *. $"' "+0"'%$ 2#$'% *. .#$#/+$+'% *. #(7 )*339(+$7 +( $"' �*2$"� �= �#(7 *. $"' ,'#$"% *))922', +( "+0"/7 )*($'($+*9% )+2)93%$#()'%I %*3' +(6*/6', %$#$' .*2)'% #(, 2'3#+( 9(2'%*/6',� ( �2,*7('� #% '/%'4"'2'� �*/+$+)#/ ,'6'/*�3'($% +( $"' /#$' ;!!�% '(%92', $"#$ $"' 3'3*27 *. %9)" '<�'2+'()'% 4*9/, )*3' $* $"' .*2' #(, �2*6+,', $"' )*($'<$ .*2 $"' %'$$+(0�9� *. $"' ��:� �"' 2+%" �'#)' �2*)'%% 2'%9/$', +( $"' %+0(+(0 *. $"' 8**, �2+,#7 �02''3'($ +( ��2+/ ;!!�� �"' '3'20'()' *. $"+% �#2$+#/ #(, 9('#%7 -�'#)'1 )2'#$', # %�#)' .*2 �'*�/' $* %$#2$ $* 2'./')$ #(, )*($'3�/#$'� �*%%+&/7 .*2 $"' .+2%$ $+3'� 4"#$ $"'7 "#, /+6', $"2*90" #(, '(,92', *6'2 $"' �#%$ $"+2$7 7'#2% *. )*(./+)$� �'$� %9)" ��= �� �2,*7(' �*33'3*2#$+*( :2*E')$� *�� )+$�� (� �� �= �9(,7 #(, �)8*6'2(� *�� )+$�� (� �� #$ 6I �2,*7(' �*33'3*2#$+*( :2*E')$� +,�� �� � C� �. $"'%'� �� 4'2' 5+//', &7 /*7#/+%$ �#2#3+/+$#2+'%� �� &7 3'3&'2% *. $"' %')92+$7 .*2)'% A�2+$+%" #237 #(, �*7#/ �/%$'2 �*(%$#&9/#27B� #(, ;� &7 6#2+*9% 2+%" 2'�9&/+)#( 02*9�%� �(*$"'2 %+< 4'2' 3'3&'2% *. $"' 2+%" �'�9&/+)#( �237 A ��B� 5+//', +(#,6'2$'($/7 4"+/' *( #)$+6' %'26+)'� *(' ,+', #))+,'($#//7� #(, +( $"2'' )#%'% +$ +% 9()/'#2 4"* 4#% 2'%�*(%+&/'� �"' 7*9(0'%$ 6+)$+3 4#% # 7*9(0 &*7 #0', ;�� #(, $"' */,'%$ # 4*3#( #0', C�� &*$" %"*$ ,'#, &7 $"' �2+$+%" #237� �"' $*$#/ *. !! ,'#$"% 2'�2'%'($% *6'2 ;� $+3'% $"' �*2$"'2( 2'/#(, )*(./+)$�2'/#$', ,'#$" 2#$' #6'2#0'� � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/ 2'./')$+*( 4#% #/%* $#5+(0 �/#)' 4"+/' /+$$/' #$$'($+*( 4#% &'+(0 0+6'( $* 3')"#(+%3% $* ,'#/ 4+$" $"' �#%$ 4+$"+( $"' .*23#/ �*/+$+)#/ �2*)'%%� ?'7 $* 9(,'2%$#(,+(0 4"#$ %"#�'% #(, +(.*23% $"' $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' 3')"#(+%3% #,*�$', +( #(7 0+6'( %+$9#$+*( #2' $"' %�')+.+) �*/+$+)#/ �*4'2 ,7(#3+)% #$ �/#7� � .*)9% *( )*339(+$7�&#%', #��2*#)"'% $* $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' 3#7� .*2 '<#3�/'� &' $"' 2'%9/$ *. # /#)5 *. +($'2'%$ #3*(0%$ ,*3+(#($ �*/+$+)#/ #)$*2% +( ,'6'/*�+(0 .*23#/ 3')"#(+%3% $* ,'#/ 4+$" $"' /'0#)7 *. $"' �#%$ #% �#2$ *. �*%$�)*(./+)$ $2#(%+$+*(� �"+% 4#% )'2$#+(/7 #( +3�*2$#($ .#)$*2 +( �*2$"'2( 2'/#(,� �"' 8**, �2+,#7 #02''3'($ 4#% # )*3�/'<� 39/$+�.#)'$', ,*)93'($ ,'#/+(0 4+$" # 4+,' 2#(0' *. +%%9'%� H*4'6'2� 4"+/' $"' #02''3'($ (*$', $"#$ $"'2' 3+0"$ &' # ('', .*2 # 2')*0(+$+*( #(, #)5(*4/',0'3'($ *. $"' �*%+$+*( *. 6+)$+3%� +$ 3#,' (* 3'($+*( *. 4"#$ .*23 $"+% 3+0"$ $#5' *2 #(7 3')"#(+%3 .*2 ,'#/+(0 4+$" $"' �#%$� �� �"+% 2'./')$', $"' 6+2$9#/ #&%'()' *. $29$" 2')*6'27 #% #( +%%9' +( $"' $#/5% /'#,+(0 9� $* $"' %+0(+(0 *. $"' #02''3'($ #(, $"' �*/+$+)#/ �2'3+93 �/#)', 9�*( #6*+,+(0 $"' �*$'($+#/ ,+6+%+6'('%% *. -,'#/+(0 4+$" $"' �#%$1� �'2$#+( $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' )*()'2(% A%9)" #% $"' 2'.*23 *. �*/+)+(0� #%�')$% *. $"' E9,+)+#/ %7%$'3� #(, $"' 2'/'#%' *. �2+%*('2%B 4'2' ,+%� #002'0#$', .2*3 '#)" *$"'2 #(, $"' �'#)' ,'#/� �+)$+3%1 +%%9'% 4'2' +(+$+#//7 ,'#/$ 4+$" +( $"' 2'�*2$ *. # �+)$+3% �*33+%%+*('2� 2'$+2', %'(+*2 )+6+/ %'26#($ ?'(('$" �/**3.+'/,� �� H*4'6'2� .*2 3#(7 (#$+*(#/+%$% #(, $"' 2'/#$+6'% *. 6+)$+3% *. %$#$' 6+*/'()'� $"' �/**3.+'/, �'�*2$ 2'�2'%'($', # 2'+(.*2)'3'($ *. 4"#$ $"'7 %#4 #% # -"+'2#2)"7 *. 6+)$+3"**,1� +( 4"+)" $"' /+6'% #(, '<�'2+'()'% *. )'2$#+( 6+)$+3% 4'2' �2+6+/'0', *6'2 #(, #&*6' *$"'2%� ( #,,+$+*(� �/**3.+'/, 4#% �2+3#2+/7 )*()'2(', 4+$" $"' )2'#$+*( *. #( #,3+(+%$2#$+6' +(.2#%$29)$92' .*2 $"' ,'/+6'27 *. �2#)$+)#/ %'26+)'% .*2 6+)$+3% 4"+/' ,'.'22+(0 #(7 ,+%)9%%+*( *. E9%$+)' +%%9'%� �"#$ %#+,� $"'2' "#, #/2'#,7 &''( %*3' %$'�% $*4#2,% $"' )2'#$+*( *. �#%$�.*)9%', E9,+)+#/ �2*)'%%'%� H*4'6'2� $"'%' 4'2' )"#20', 4+$" '<#3+(+(0 �#2$+)9/#2 +()+,'($% *2 .#)'$% *. $"' )*(./+)$ A.*2 '<#3�/'� $"' �#6+//' (G9+27 %'$ 9� +( ;!!C $* 2'� '<#3+(' $"' '6'($% *. �/**,7 �9(,#7� �#(9#27 ;!C�B� �$ $"' %#3' $+3'� �9&/+) ,'&#$' *( $"'%' +(G9+2+'%� 6+)$+3%� #(, -,'#/+(0 4+$" $"' �#%$1 "#, #/%* &')*3' '3&2*+/', 4+$" $"' �2*�*%', '#2/7 2'/'#%' *. )*(./+)$�2'/#$', �2+%*('2%� #(, $"' "+0"/7 6*)#/ *��*%+$+*( *. # (93&'2 *. ('4/7 )2'#$', A3#+(/7 �(+*(+%$B 6+)$+3% 02*9�% $* $"' %#3'� $ 4#% #0#+(%$ $"+% &#)5,2*� $"#$ #( #, "*) 02*9� +( �2,*7(' *. 6+)$+3%1 2'/#$+6'%� +($'2'%$', +(,+6+,9#/%� #(, )*339(+$7 #)$+6+%$% ,')+,',� #.$'2 # %'2+'% *. �9&/+) 3''$+(0%� $* �2*,9)' # &**5 $"#$ 4*9/, )*($#+( $"' $'%$+� 3*(+'% *. $"' 2'/#$+6'%� .2+'(,%� #(, '7'4+$('%%'% *. $"' #2'#1% 6+)$+3%� �"+% 4#% ,'%+0(', $* �2*6+,' 2')*0(+$+*( $* $"*%' 4"* "#, &''( 5+//', #(, A�#2$+)9/#2/7 +( $'23% $"' 6+)$+3% *. %$#$' 6+*/'()'B $* )"#//'(0' 4"#$ 4#% ��� �� �02''3'($ 2'#)"', +( $"' 39/$+��#2$7 ('0*$+#$+*(%� ;� ��2+/ ;!!�� �� ?� �/**3.+'/,� ;� ���� 3������� ����8 3�� �� � ��� " ������ ������� =������ $ ������ ��� A;!!CB ��� � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/ %''( #% # -"+'2#2)"7 *. 6+)$+3%1� �// A'<)'�$ *('B *. $"' )*33+$$'' 3'3&'2% 4'2' .2*3 �2,*7('� �2*3 $"' *9$%'$ $"' ��: 4#% $"'2'.*2' #( '($+2'/7 )*339(+$7�+(%�+2', +(+$+#$+6'� �+$'2#//7 ,*F'(% *. �2,*7(' �'*�/' )*($2+� &9$', $* $"' �2*E')$1% 4*25 $"2*90" $"'+2 +(6*/6'3'($ 4+$" +($'26+'4%� ,#$#&#%' )*//#$+*(� $2#(%)2+&+(0� 2'$92(+(0 ',+$', +($'26+'4%� �2**. 2'#,+(0� #(, 6#2+*9% *$"'2 $#%5%� �"+% )2'#$', 3#(7 ,+..+)9/$+'% &9$ $"' #,6#($#0'% A$"#$ +%� *. %5+//% ,'6'/*�3'($ #(, +( 0#+(+(0 #))'%%B .#2 *9$4'+0"', $"'%' �2*&/'3%� �"' �2,*7(' �*33'3*2#$+*( :2*E')$ )#( &' )"#2#)$'2+F', #% #( '<#3�/' *. :#2$+)+�#$*27 �)$+*( �'%'#2)" A:��B� #% ,+%)9%%', +( ,'$#+/ +( $"' %')$+*( #&*6'� ( �#2$ $"+% +% &')#9%' %9)" �'2%�')$+6'% ,+2')$/7 +(./9'()', $"' 4*25+(0% *. $"' 02*9�� H*4'6'2� $"' 2'/#$+*(%"+� &'$4''( $"' :�� #(, $"' ��: +% '6'( 3*2' #��#2'($ 4"'( 6+'4+(0 $"' �2*E')$ 4+$" $"' &'('.+$ *. "+(,%+0"$� �$ +$% 3*%$ %$2#+0"$.*24#2, :�� +% ,'.+(', &7 $4* 5'7 +($'2� )*((')$', '/'3'($%� +$ +% -#)$+*( 2'%'#2)" $"#$ +% �#2$+)+�#$*27 #(, �#2$+)+� �#$*27 2'%'#2)" $"#$ 9(+$'% 4+$" #)$+*(1� �C �"' #,*�$+*( *. :�� %$2#$'0+'% #(, 3'$"*,*/*0+'% 4#% )'($2#/ $* $"' 4*25 *. $"' ��:� (,'',� $"' �2+()+�/' *. �#2$+)+�#$+*(� ,'.+(', &7 $"' -'3&',,',1 )"#2#)$'2 *. $"' �2*E')$� 4#% $"' ��:1% )*2' )*()'�$� �"' '<�'2+'()' *. $"' 2'%'#2)" $"'2'.*2' �2*6+,'% +(%+0"$% *( $"' 2*/' *. :�� +( 2'%*/6+(0 %9)" 0'('2+) 2'%'#2)" +%%9'% #% #))'%%� -*�'(�('%%1� #(, 9%'� �"' +%%9' *. �#2$+)+�#$+*( +% �#2$+)9/#2/7 2'/'6#($ A#(, �*$'($+#//7 �2*&/'3#$+)B +( # ,+6+,', %*)+'$7 /+5' �*2$"'2( 2'/#(,� �"' #2$+)/' #209'% $"#$� 4"+/' -+($'2�)*339(+$71 4*25 3#7 &' #��2*�2+#$' +( 3#(7 )+2)93%$#()'%� $"'2' #2' #/%* # (93&'2 *. 3'$"*,*/*0+)#/ �2*&/'3% 4+$" %9)" #( #��2*#)"� ( ,'#/+(0 4+$" )'2$#+( +%%9'% +( )'2$#+( #2'#%� +$ 4+// &' %900'%$',� $"'2' #2' �*%+$+6' *9$)*3'% +( 9(,'2$#5+(0 A4"#$ "#% &''( ,'%)2+&', #%B -%+(0/'�+,'($+$71 4*25� �"' +%%9' *. �#2$+)+�#$+*( +% #/%* �#2$+)9/#2/7 %+0(+.+)#($ +( $"' #2'# *. �*%$�)*(./+)$ -$29$"�$'//+(01 4*25� �7 �/#)+(0 -�#2$+)+�#$+*(1 #$ $"' "'#2$ *. +$% #��2*#)"� $"' ��: )*($'%$', # (93&'2 *. +,'#% $"#$ #2' )922'($/7 "+0"/7 +(./9'($+#/ )*()'2(+(0 $"' �92�*%' #(, )*(,9)$ *. �*%$�)*(./+)$ -$29$" $'//+(01� �"' -)*339(+$7�&#%',1 (#$92' *. $"' ��: )#( &' )*($2#%$', $* 3*2' +(%$+$9$+*(#/+F',� -$*��,*4(1 $29$"�$'//+(0 3')"#(+%3%� ( �#2$+)9/#2� $"' %$2'%% *( -�#2$+)+�#$+*(1 �2*3*$', #( '<�/+)+$/7 -6+)$+3�)'($2',1 #0'(,#� �"+% #��2*#)" )"#//'(0', $"' �*%%+&/' 2'/'0#$+*( *. $"' +($'2'%$% *. -6+)$+3%1 #(, �#2$+)+�#($% $* %9)" 4+,'2 %*)+#/ 0*#/% #% -(#$+*(�&9+/,+(01 #(, -2')*()+/+#$+*(1� �&6+*9%/7 $"'%' '(,% 3#7 &' "+0"/7 ,'%+2#&/'� H*4'6'2� $"' #2$+)/' #209'% $"#$� .*2 2'%'#2)"'2% 4*25+(0 +( $"+% .+'/,� $"'2' +% # ('', $* 3#+($#+( # 6'27 )/'#2 .*)9% *( $"' G9'%$+*( *. 4"*3 A#(, 4"#$B -$29$"� $'//+(01 +% �2+3#2+/7 .*2J $ +% %900'%$', $"#$ # :���+(.*23', #��2*#)" $* #// %$#0'% *. $"' 2'%'#2)" �2*)'%% )#( "'/� $* �2*3*$' E9%$ %9)" # .*)9%� ( $92(� $"+% 3#7 '(%92' $"#$ -)*339(+$7�&#%', $29$"�$'//+(01� &7 -0+6+(0 6*+)'1 #(, ��� �C �#"3#(� *�� )+$�� (� �=� �� C�� � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/ #+,+(0 $"' -2'%$*2#$+*( *. ,+0(+$71 )#( #,6#()' 2'#/ �2*02'%%+6' %*)+#/ )"#(0'� �� ( .#)$ )*339(+$7 �#2$+)+�#$+*( 4#% #/4#7% %''( #% $"' ,'.+(+(0 .'#$92' *. $"' ��:� �"' +,'# *. '3&',,',('%% 9(,'2�+((', $"' �"+/*%*�"7 #(, �2*)'%% $* '(%92' $"#$ $"' )*339(+$7 +( '..')$ $**5 -*4('2%"+�1 #(, )*($2*/ *. $"' ,'%+0(� 2'%'#2)" �2*)'%%� ',+$+(0� 2'$92( �"#%'� #(, �2*,9)$+*( *. $"' &**5� ( �2#)$+)#/ $'23% $"' 02#%%2**$% (#$92' *. $"' �2*E')$ 4#% )29)+#/ +( *2,'2 $* 0#+( $29%$� '(#&/' #))'%%� #(, '%$#&/+%" #( '3�#$"'$+) 2'/#$+*(%"+� 4+$" $"' +($'26+'4''%� �"' ��: %#4 +$%'/. #% �2*6+,+(0 # 3'#(% .*2 +(,+6+,9#/% #(, )*339(+$7 $* '<�2'%% +$%'/. #(, $* �/#)' �2'6+*9%/7 9(2')*2,', '<�'2+'()'% +($* $"' �9&/+) ,*3#+(� �*)#/ )*($2*/ 4#% $"'2'.*2' %''( #% #( #&%*/9$' 2'G9+2'3'($ .*2 $"+% $* &' #)"+'6',� �"+% 4#% �#2$+)9/#2/7 +3�*2$#($ &')#9%' *. $"' ,''��%'#$', ,+%$29%$ *. -*9$%+,'2%1 2'%9/$+(0 .2*3 $"' /*(0 7'#2% *. )*(./+)$ #(, %926'+//#()'� �* &' #( -+(%+,'21 +( # �/#)' /+5' �2,*7(' 3'#($ $"#$ +(,+6+,9#/% "#, $* "#6' $"' .9// )*3�/'3'($ *. )2','($+#/% #(,D*2 /+.' '<�'2+'()'% A/*)#/ &#)502*9(,� .#3+/7 #(, .2+'(,%"+� /+(5%� %�')+.+) �*/+$+)#/ "+%$*27� #(, %* *(B $* #)"+'6' +(%+,'2 %$#$9%� �! �"' (#$92' *. $"' ��: #//*4', +$ #))'%% $* 02*9�%� 6*+)'%� #(, 5(*4/',0' $"#$ 4*9/, *$"'24+%' "#6' &''( +(#))'%%+&/' *2 -*9$�*.�&*9(,%1 .*2 #( -*9$%+,'21� �6'24"'/3+(0/7� 2'%�*(,'($% .'/$ $"#$ $"' %'(%+$+6+$+'% *. $"' �2*E')$ (')'%%+$#$', $"' 9%' *. -+(%+,'2%1 #(, +(,+6+,9#/% $"#$ 4'2' 2'%�')$', #(, 2**$', +( $"' )*339(+$7� ( # )*339(+$7 $"#$ "#% '<�'2+'()', ,')#,'% *. %926'+//#()'� %9%�+)+*( *. *9$%+,'2% #%5+(0 G9'%$+*(% +% # 2'#/+$7� �*2 2'%�*(,'($% $"+% 4#% )/*%'/7 #%%*)+#$', 4+$" $"' +%%9' *. #))'%% #(, $29%$� �"' 9%' *. -+(%+,'2%1 %"*9/, $* &' &#/#()', #0#+(%$ �*%%+&/' ('0#$+6' +3�#)$%� $ 3+0"$ &' $"' )#%' $"#$ .*2 # 6#2+'$7 *. 2'#%*(% /*)#/% 3#7 &' 2'$+)'($ #&*9$ -*�'(+(0 9�1 $* #( -+(%+,'21 4"+)" )*9/, /'#, $* �#2$+#/ #))*9($%� �'+(0 )/*%' $* $"' %9&E')$ 3#$$'2 3+0"$ #/%* �2*,9)' #( +(#&+/+$7 $* -%''1 $"' 6#/+,+$7 *. )*3�'$+(0 #2093'($% *2 $* G9'%$+*( )'2$#+( #))*9($%� �"*%' +(6*/6', +( $"+% $7�' *. 4*25 ('', $* &' 3+(,.9/ *. %9)" -"+,,'(1 $'(%+*(%� *2 �*%%+&/' 9('G9#/ �*4'2 2'/#$+*(% #(, 2'./')$ 9�*( $"'+2 �2#)$+)' #$ '6'27 %$#0' *. $"' �2*)'%%� �/*(0%+,' /*)#/ �#2$+)+�#$+*( #(, )*($2*/� +()/9%+6+$7 4#% %''( #% # 5'7 �2+()+�/' *. $"' �2*E')$1% '$"*%� �"' )2+$'2+*( .*2 +()/9%+*( +( $"' &**5 4#% $"#$ $"' 6+)$+3 "#, $* "#6' &''( # 2'%+,'($ *. �2,*7(' .*2 #$ /'#%$ %*3' �*+($ +( $"'+2 /+.'� � .#2 /'%% )"#//'(0+(0 #��2*#)" .*2 $"' �2*E')$ 4*9/, "#6' &''( $* .*)9% '<)/9%+6'/7 *( ,'#$"% 2'%9/$+(0 .2*3 %$#$' #(, /*7#/+%$ #)$+*(% #(, $* +0(*2' $"*%' )#%'% $"#$ +(6*/6', 2'�9&/+)#( 5+//+(0%� �'3&'2% *. $"' �2*E')$ 2'0#2,', $"'+2 2'3+$ #% #( +()/9%+6' #��2*#)" $* -$29$"�$'//+(01 +( $"#$ +$ ,+, (*$ �2')/9,' #(7*(' *( $"' &#%+% *. $"'+2 '$"(+)D2'/+0+*9% +,'($+$7� �*/+$+)#/ #..+/+#$+*(� #(,D*2 %$#$9% #% # 6+)$+3� �"+% +( 3#(7 4#7% 4#% $"' %$2'(0$" *. $"' �2*E')$� ��C �� �*2 # 3*2' ,'$#+/', ,+%)9%%+*( *. $"' )*()'�$9#/ #(, 3'$"*,*/*0+)#/ #��2*#)" *. $"' ��:� 2'#, �9(,7 #(, �)8*6'2(� *�� )+$� A����B� (� �� �! �9(,7 #(, �)8*6'2(� *�� )+$�� (� �� ��� C� !� � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/ �� ' �� �������� ��� � ����� �� � ��� � �� �� � �"' 4*25 *. $"' �2*E')$ $**5 .*92 7'#2% #(, 2'%9/$', +( $"' �9&/+)#$+*( *. # &**5 A!�� ���8 ��� )�� �� �� ��B +( ���� $"#$ 4#% &#%', #2*9(, $"' ',+$', $'%$+3*(+'% *. +($'26+'4''%� �6'2 ��� +($'26+'4% 4'2' )#22+', *9$� �"' /+%$ *. +($'26+'4''% 4#% #22+6', #$ +( )*(%9/$#$+*( 4+$" $"' .#3+/+'%� #(, 9%9#//7 +()/9,', # .#3+/7 3'3&'2� )/*%' .2+'(, #(,� 4"'2' �*%%+&/'� #( '7'4+$('%%� �// $"' +($'26+'4% )#22+', *9$ .*2 $"' �2*E')$ 4'2' 2')*2,',� $2#(%)2+&',� #(, ',+$',� �"' +(+$+#/ ',+$', 6'2%+*( 4#% $"'( "#(,', &#)5 $* #(, ,+%)9%%', 4+$" $"' +($'26+'4''� �"'7 4'2' 0+6'( # �'2+*, *. $+3' $* $#/5 $"+% *6'2 4+$" 3'3&'2% *. $"'+2 .#3+/7 #(, $* #/$'2 $"'+2 $'%$+3*(7 +( #(7 4#7 $"'7 .'/$ (')'%%#27� �"+% "#(,+(0�&#)5 �"#%' #,,', 9(.*2'%''( 7'#2% $* $"' 4*25/*#, *. $"' �2*E')$ &9$ 4#% 2'0#2,', #% # 5'7 '/'3'($ *. +$% 4*25+(0 �2*)'%%� $ '(%92', $"#$ +($'26+'4''% "#, # %'(%' *. )*($2*/ #(, *4('2%"+� *6'2 4"#$ 4#% 42+$$'(� :#2$+)+�#($% 4'2' #/%* 0+6'( �2'��9&/+)#$+*( #))'%% $* $"' � ������ )#%' %$9,7 $"#$ +()/9,', +($'26+'4% 4+$" *$"'2 .#3+/7 3'3&'2%� .2+'(,%� #(, '7'4+$('%%'%� �"#(0'% )*9/, *(/7 &' 3#,' $* *('1% *4( $'%$+3*(7 &9$ �#2$+)+�#($% 4'2' '()*92#0', $* &2+(0 $* $"' #$$'($+*( *. $"' ��: #(7 +(#))92#)+'% *2 +%%9'% *. )*()'2( +( $"' )*($'($ *. *$"'2 $'%$+3*(+'%� �#3+/+'% #(, .2+'(,% *.$'( ,+%)9%%', $"'%' +%%9'% #$ 02'#$ /'(0$" #3*(0%$ $"'3%'/6'% #(, 4+$" 3'3&'2% *. $"' �2*E')$� �"' ��: $**5 02'#$ )#2' $* ,+%)9%% #(, #%%'%% $"' /+5'/7 +3�#)$ *. #(7 ('4 +(.*23#$+*( )*($#+(', +( $'%$+3*(+'%� �"'7 %*90"$ #,6+)' .2*3 5'7 +(,+6+,9#/% )/*%' $* $"' .#3+/7 +( G9'%$+*( #(, /*)#/ 6+)$+3%1 02*9�% #&*9$ 4#7% +( 4"+)" $* �2'�#2' 2'/#$+6'% .*2 $"+% ('4%� :2*6+,+(0 # )*(,9+$ *. )*($#)$ 4#% *.$'( 5'7 $* 2'%*/6+(0 ,+..'2� '()'% *. *�+(+*(� �"' 4*25 4#% 9(,*9&$',/7 ,+..+)9/$ #(, )"#//'(0+(0 .*2 #// +(6*/6',� :2*6+,+(0 $"' .9// )#%' %$9,7 $* $"' .#3+/7 *. $"' 6+)$+3 �2*6+,', #( *��*2$9(+$7 .*2 .#3+/+'% $* /'#2( #&*9$ $"' )+2)93%$#()'% %922*9(,+(0 $"'+2 )#%' #(, "'/�', '(%92' $"#$ #(7 �2*&/'3% *2 +%%9'% )*9/, &' 2'%*/6', �2+*2 $* �9&/+)#$+*(� 8+6'( $"' "+0"/7 �'2%*(#/ #(, %'(%+$+6' (#$92' *. $"' 4*25 $"+% 4#% )29)+#/� �"'2' 4'2' #/%* *))#%+*(% 4"'( �'*�/' %*90"$ .92$"'2 )/#2+.+)#$+*( #&*9$ $"' +()+,'($� *2 .2*3 *$"'2 02*9�% *2 *20#(+F#$+*(% +( 2'/#$+*( $* $"' ,'#$"� %9)" #% $"' 2'�9&/+)#( 3*6'3'($� �( *&6+*9% /+3+$#$+*( *. %9)" # �2*E')$� #% ,+%)9%%', &'/*4� +% $"#$ +$ ,*'% (*$ "#6' #))'%% $* *..+)+#/ 2')*2,% #(, #// )*3&#$#($ 02*9�% +(6*/6', +( $"' )*(./+)$� �*$4+$"� %$#(,+(0 $"+%� $"' ��: 3#,' '6'27 '..*2$ $* 0'$ #(%4'2% $* G9'%$+*(% #(, $* 2'%*/6' *9$%$#(,+(0 +%%9'% 4"'('6'2 �*%%+&/'� �*2 $"+%� $"' /*)#/ )"#2#)$'2 *. $"' �2*E')$ 4#% '%%'($+#/� 8'('2#$+(0 /*)#/ #0'()7 #% # 3'#(% $* '3�*4'2+(0 �#2$+)+�#($% 4#% # )'($2#/ #+3 +( $"+%I +$ 4#% $29$" 2')*6'27 &'+(0 �/#7', *9$ #$ +$% 3*%$ +($+3#$' /'6'/� �"#$ %#+,� $"' �2*&/'3 *. 2*3#($+)+F+(0 %9)" (*$+*(% #% -)*339(+$71 #(, -'3�*4'23'($1 %"*9/, #/4#7% &' 5'�$ +( 3+(, +( *2,'2 $* )*9($'2 $"' �*$'($+#/ *. 3#(+�9/#$+*( #(, #&9%' 3#%5+(0 3#20+(#/+F#$+*( #(, '<)/9%+*(� �$"'24+%'� #��#2'($ ��� � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/ -�#2$+)+�#$+*(1 )#( '($2'()" #(, 2'�2*,9)' 2#$"'2 $"#( )"#//'(0' �*4'2 2'/#$+*(%� !� �'6'2#/ )*339(+$7 .*293% #(, �9&/+) 3''$+(0% 4'2' #/%* *20#(+F',� $* 4"+)" 6+)$+3%1 2'/#$+6'% #/4#7% 2')'+6', �'2%*(#/ +(6+$#$+*(%� �"' 3''$+(0% A0'('2#//7 4'//�#$$'(,', &7 #% 3#(7 #% ��� �'*�/'B #//*4', �'*�/' $* &' 9�,#$', *( $"' ��:1% 4*25 &9$� �'2"#�% 3*2' +3�*2$#($/7� $"'7 4'2' ,'%+0(', $* )2'#$' # �9&/+) %�#)' .*2 *�'( ,+#/*09' #&*9$ "+0"/7 %'(%+$+6' +%%9'% $"#$ +( $"' �#%$ "#, &''( -9(%�*5'( *2 $#&**1 %9&E')$%� �*2 '<#3�/'� ;� /*)#/ �'*�/' "#, &''( 5+//', &7 6#2+*9% 2'�9&/+)#( *20#(+F#$+*(%� %*3' #% #//'0', +(.*23'2%� �"'%' 4'2' #3*(0 $"' 3*%$ )"#//'(0+(0 )#%'% $"' ��: "#, $* ,'#/ 4+$" #(, .''/+(0% 2#( "+0" 4"'( %9)" +%%9'% 4'2' ,+%)9%%',� �"'2' +% (* ,*9&$ $"' %9&E')$ 3#$$'2 4#% )"#//'(0+(0 .*2 $"' ��: #(, )*339(+$7 #/+5'� %$+22+(0 �#+(.9/ 3'3*2+'% .*2 3#(7� �*2 *$"'2% +$ �2*6*5', 39)" %*9/ %'#2)"+(0 #(, 2'./')$+*(� �"' 0*#/% *. $"' ��: #(, $"' �2*)'%% +$ 0'('2#$', 4'2' $"'2'.*2' )/'#2/7 3*2' )*3�/'< #(, ,''�'2 $"#( )*//')$+(0 +($'26+'4% .*2 # &**5� �7 �9%"+(0 $"' &*9(,#2+'% *. 4"#$ 4#% -#))'�$#&/'1 $* #2$+)9/#$'� $"' �2*)'%% 4#% +( 3#(7 4#7% /#7+(0 $"' .*9(,#$+*( .*2 # )*339(+$7 ,2+6'( -$29$"�$'//+(01 �2*)'%%� �� (���� ��� ��� �������� �� �"' #9$"*2% )#22+', *9$ # .*//*4�9� %$9,7 4"'( $"' �2*E')$ '(,', $* .+(, *9$ 4"#$ 4#% 2'0#2,', #% +$% %$2'(0$"% #(, 4'#5('%%'%� !; �"' ,+%)9%%+*( $"#$ .*//*4% ,2#4% 9�*( $"' '6#/9#$+*( .+(,+(0% #(, �2*6+,'% +(%+0"$% +($* %*3' *. $"' 4#7% +( 4"+)" '(0#0+(0 +( $"' �2*E')$ +3�#)$', 9�*( +(,+6+,9#/%� $"'+2 .#3+/+'%� #(, $"' 4+,'2 �2,*7(' )*339(+$7 #(, &'7*(,� �% (*$', +( $"' +($2*,9)$*27 �#2#02#�"� $"+% )#%' %$9,7 +//9%$2#$'% $"' 4#7% +( 4"+)" # &*$$*3�9� -$29$"�$'//+(01 �2*)'%% )#( 3#5' # %+0(+.+)#($ )*($2+&9$+*( $* $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)'� �')*0(+$+*( #(, #)5(*4/',0'3'($ 4'2' )+$', #% #( +3�*2$#($ *9$)*3' *. $"' ��:� �"' �2*)'%% *..'2', # %�#)' .*2 +(,+6+,9#/% $* $'// $"'+2 %$*27 #(, .*2 �2'6+*9%/7 '<)/9,', *2 3#20+(#/+F', 6*+)'% $* &')*3' �#2$ *. �9&/+) ,+%)*92%'� �"' 2'%$*2#$+*( *. ,+0(+$7� $"2*90" 2')*0(+$+*( #(, #)5(*4/',0'� 3'($ +( $"' &**5� �#2$+)9/#2/7 $* $"' .#3+/+'% *. #//'0', +(.*23'2%� 4#% 2'0#2,', #% # %+0(+.+)#($ *9$)*3' *. $"' �2*E')$� �"' 2'/#$+6'% *. 6+)$+3% *. %$#$' 6+*/'()' 4'2' #/%* �2*6+,', $"' *��*2$9(+$7 $* )"#//'(0' 4"#$ $"'7 �'2)'+6', #% $"' -,'(+#/ *. $29$"1 +( *..+)+#/ #))*9($% #(, 0+6'( �9&/+) ��! !� "+$'� *�� )+$�� (� C!� �� �� !; �9(,7 #(, �)8*6'2(� *�� )+$�� (� �� �"' 2'%'#2)" %'$ *9$ $* )2+$+)#//7 #%%'%% $"' +3�#)$� 6#/9'� #(, /+3+$% *. $"' 4*25 *. $"' ��: #% #( '<#3�/' *. )*339(+$7 -$29$"� $'//+(01� � %'2+'% *. �� +(�,'�$" +($'26+'4% 4'2' )#22+', *9$� ,'%+0(', $* '/+)+$ $"' 6+'4% #(, '<�'2+'()'% *. # %#3�/' *. 5'7 2'%�*(,'($ 02*9�% +()/9,+(0 $"*%' 4"* "#, �#2$+)+�#$', +( $"' �2*E')$ A0#6' $'%$+3*(7B� 2'%+,'($% *. �2,*7(' A(*(��#2$+)+�#($%B� #(, $"' &2*#,'2 (#$+*(#/+%$ #(, �(+*(+%$ )*339(+$+'%� � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/ 2')*0(+$+*( +( $"' &**5� #/$"*90" $"' /#)5 *. %$#$' #)5(*4/',03'($ 4#% # )29)+#/ /+3+$#$+*(� H*4'6'2� $"' &*$$*3�9� #��2*#)" *. $"' ��: "'/�', '(%92' $"#$ $"' �2*)'%% *. 0#+(+(0 2')*0(+$+*( #(, #)5(*4/',0'3'($ 4#% *(' +( 4"+)" 6+)$+3%1 #(, 2'/#$+6'% .'/$ $"'3%'/6'% $* &' #)$+6' �#2$+)+�#($%� 2#$"'2 $"#( �#%%+6' 2')+�+'($% *. -$29$"�$'//+(01� �*339(+$7 �#2$+)+�#$+*( %$**, *9$ #% $"' %+(0/' 3*%$ +3�*2$#($ #%�')$ *. $"' ��: �2*)'%% .*2 $"' 3#E*2+$7 *. �#2$+)+�#($% +($'26+'4', #(, +(,'', $"' 4+,'2 )*339(+$7� �"' 3'$"*, *. "#(,+(0 &#)5 ',+$', $'%$+3*(+'% )2'#$', # %'(%' *. +(,+6+,9#/ #(, )*//')$+6' *4('2%"+� #(, 4#% 2'0#2,', #% # .9(,#� 3'($#/ %$2'(0$" #(, �*%+$+6' *9$)*3' *. $"' �2*E')$� $ +% +( 0#+(+(0 ,+2')$ )*($2*/ *. $"' 5(*4/',0' �2*,9)', $"2*90" %9)" 4*25 $"#$ '3�*4'23'($ $#5'% �/#)'� ( E9%$ $"' %#3' 4#7� # 6+)$+3�)'($'2', -$29$"�$'//+(01 �2*)'%% ('',% $* �/#)' $"' &'#2'2 *. $'%$+3*(7 #$ $"' "'#2$ *. $"' ,')+%+*(�3#5+(0 �2*)'%%� �6'24"'/3+(0/7 +$ 4#% .'/$ $"#$ $"' %'(%+$+6+$+'% *. $"' �2*E')$ (')'%%+$#$', $"' 9%' *. -+(%+,'2%1 #(, +(,+6+,9#/% $"#$ 4'2' 2'%�')$', #(, 2**$', +( $"' )*339(+$7� � 5'7 +%%9' *. )*()'2( 4"'( ,*+(0 %9)" %'(%+$+6' 4*25 +% $"' +%%9' *. $29%$� �(,'2$#5+(0 4*25 4+$" -+(%+,'2%1 $29%$', &7 /*)#/ �'*�/' )2'#$', .#2 02'#$'2 �*%%+&+/+$+'% #(, �2*,9)', $"' %*2$ *. 5(*4/',0' *.$'( -"+,,'(1 .2*3 -*9$%+,'2%1� �(7 �2*)'%% ,'6+%+(0 4+,'2 %$2#$'0+'% $* ,'#/ 4+$" $"' /'0#)7 *. $"' �#%$ ('',% $* &' )*(%)+*9% *. $"' �2*&/'3% *. #))'%%+(0 %9)" '<�'2+'()'%� �"' 9%' *. -+(%+,'2%1 )*9/, E9%$ #% )*()'+6#&/7 '<)/9,' )'2$#+( -6*+)'%1 #(, /'#, $* 09#2,', #(, �#2$+#/ #))*9($% #(, %'/.� )'(%*2%"+�� $ +% $"'2'.*2' +3�'2#$+6' $"#$ $"*%' +(6*/6', +( %9)" 4*25 #2' )*(%)+*9% *. $"+% $'(%+*( #(, #2' .9//7 2'./')$+6' +( $"'+2 �2#)$+)' $"2*90"*9$� !� ($2#�)*339(+$7 )*(./+)$ 2'%*/9$+*( 4#% $"' 3*%$ .2'G9'($/7 3'($+*(', �*%+$+6' *9$)*3'% *. $"' ��: �2*)'%%� � %+0(+.+)#($ )*($2+&9$+*( *. &*$$*3� 9� �#2$+)+�#$*27 -$29$"�$'//+(01 +% +$% )#�#)+$7 $* 0'$ $* $"' (+$$7�02+$$7 *. +($2#� )*339(+$7 )*(./+)$� 9(,'2%$#(, $"' ,7(#3+)%� #(, &' #&/' $* 2'%*/6' )'2$#+( 9(2'%*/6', +%%9'%� �2,*7(' +% (*$ # "*3*0'(*9% )*339(+$7 #(, $"'2' #2' 6'27 2'#/ #(, /*(0�%$#(,+(0 ,+6+%+*(%� %*3' *. 4"+)" #2' # &7��2*,9)$ *. $"' �*/+$+)#/ )*(./+)$� �"' �2*E')$ )2'#$', # �2*)'%% *2 3')"#(+%3 $* ,'#/ 4+$" ,+..+)9/$ +($'2(#/ )*(./+)$�2'/#$', +%%9'% #(, �2*3*$', 2'%*/9$+*( *. 4"#$ 4'2' *.$'( %''( #% -$#&** %9&E')$%1 #$ # (93&'2 *. ,+..'2'($ /'6'/%� �"' '<�'2+'()' *. $"' ��: 4*9/, %900'%$ $"#$ # &*$$*3�9� �#2$+)+�#$*27 #��2*#)" )#( 3#5' # %+0(+.+)#($ )*($2+&9$+*( $* )2'#$+(0 ,+#/*09' #$ $"' )*339(+$7 /'6'/� �(' *. $"' 3*%$ %'2+*9% /+3+$#$+*(% *. 9(*..+)+#/ &*$$*3�9� �2*)'%%'% +( 0'('2#/ +% $"'+2 +(#&+/+$7 $* 9()*6'2 �2'6+*9%/7 9(5(*4( +(.*23#$+*( .2*3 *9$%+,' #0'()+'%� *&$#+(+(0 %*3' .*23 *. *..+)+#/ 2')*0(+$+*( *2 2')*3�'(%'� *2 +( �92%9+(0 #))*9($#&+/+$7� �"#$ %#+,� *..+)+#/ $29$"�2')*6'27 +(+$+#$+6'% )#( $"'3%'/6'% .#)' "90' �2*&/'3% +( $"+% 2'0#2,� (*$ /'#%$ $"2*90" $"' )*($+(9', *��*%+$+*( #(, /#)5 *. )**�'2#$+*( *. %$#$' #0'()+'% $* .+(,+(0 4#7% *. �!� !� �9(,7 #(, �)8*6'2(� *�� )+$�� (� �� ��� �� C� � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/ ,'#/+(0 4+$" �#%$ +(E9%$+)'� !� �*$$*3�9� 9(*..+)+#/ �2*)'%%'% )#( &' 3*2' #,'�$ #$ 9()*6'2+(0 �2'6+*9%/7 -"+,,'( $29$"%1 $"#$ )#( /'#, *( $* *$"'2 $"+(0%� �"'7 )#( &' "+0"/7 '..')$+6' +( &9+/,+(0 # -)#%' $* #(%4'21� �/#7+(0 # 6+$#/ 2*/' +( ,*)93'($+(0 "93#( 2+0"$% #&9%'% #(, �#$$'2(% *. 6+*/#$+*(% $"#$ 3#5' +$ +()2'#%+(0/7 ,+..+)9/$ .*2 $"' %$#$' $* )*($+(9' $* ,'(7 )9/�#&+/+$7� �*2 %*3' +($'26+'4''% -$29$"�$'//+(01 4#% 2'0#2,', #% �#2$ *.� &9$ (*$ # %9&%$+$9$' .*2� %''5+(0 E9%$+)'� �"'2' 4#% # %'(%' .*2 %*3' +( 4"+)" $"' 2')*0(+$+*( ,'2+6', .2*3 $"'+2 +(6*/6'3'($ +( $"' �2*E')$ 4#% +$%'/. # A%9..+)+'($B .*23 *. E9%$+)'� ( $"'%' )+2)93%$#()'%� -$29$"1 +% 9%', $* ,'(*9()' *2 )"#//'(0' # �'2)'+6', +(E9%$+)'� �*2 *$"'2% $"+% 4#% (*$ $"' )#%' #(, $"'7 %#4 # ('', .*2 /'0#/ #(, E9,+)+#/ #6'(9'% $* &' �92%9', #% $"*2*90"/7 #% �*%%+&/'� �+(#//7� �'2"#�% $"' 3*%$ %+0(+.+)#($ /+3+$#$+*( *. #// .*2 $"' ��: )*()'2(', $"' ,+..+)9/$+'% *. )*(,9)$+(0 %9)" %'(%+$+6' 2'%'#2)" -#)2*%% $"' ,+6+,'1� �"+% )'2$#+(/7 �2*6', $* &' #( +%%9' .*2 $"' ��:� :2*E')$% 4+$" # %+(0/' +,'($+$7 .*)9% )#// +($* G9'%$+*( $"' 6#/+,+$7 *. $"' -9($*/, $29$"%1 $"'7 #2' #&/' $* $'//� $"*90" #0#+(� %9)" )2+$+)+%3% )#( #/%* &' /'6'//', #$ %$#$'�/', �2*)'%%'%� != ������� �� "#$ 4' "#6' %*90"$ $* #209' "'2' +% $"#$ $"' )922'($ ,*3+(#($ )*()'�$+*(% *. $2#(%+$+*(� E9%$+)'� #(, ,'3*)2#)7� 4+$"+( $"' )*($'<$ *. $"' �2'6#+/+(0 �*%$�)*(./+)$ #0'(,#� $'(, $* ,'/+3+$ $"' �*$'($+#/ *. %*)+#/ #(, �*/+$+)#/ )"#(0' +( �*%$�)*(./+)$ %*)+'$+'%� ( %* ,*+(0 $"'7 )#( #)$ $* ,'(7 $"' 0'(9+(' '<'2)+%' *. 2+0"$% #(, $"' �2*3*$+*( *. #)$+6' �*/+$+)#/ #0'()7 *( $"' �#2$ *. $"'+2 �*�9/#$+*(%� �"+% +% # �2#)$+)#/ #% 4'// #% # $"'*2'$+)#/ +%%9'� �9%$#+(� #&+/+$7 +% 5'7 $* $"' /*(0�$'23 %9))'%% *. #(7 �*%$�)*(./+)$ E9%$+)' �2*02#33'� �"*%' )*()'+6', #(, +3�*%', .2*3 $"' $*� ,*4( $"#$ ,* (*$ "#6' /*)#/ *4('2%"+� #(, 0'(9+(' �#2$+)+�#$+*(� #2' .#2 /'%% /+5'/7 $* "#6' /'0+$+3#)7� &' '..')$+6'� #(, $"'2'.*2' %9%$#+(#&/' #.$'2 $"' %�*(%*2% /'#6'� ' #2' (*$ %900'%$+(0 $"#$ &*$$*3�9� +(+$+#$+6'% 2'�2'%'($ #( #/$'2(#$+6' $* $"' '<+%$+(0 $*��,*4( #��2*#)"'%� "#$ 4' #2' #209+(0� #(, "#6' %*90"$ $* +//9%$2#$' 4+$" $"' �2,*7(' )#%' %$9,7� +% $"#$ # &*$$*3�9�� �#2$+)+�#$*27 -$29$"�$'//+(01 #��2*#)" "#% �#2$+)9/#2 %$2'(0$"% #(, 39)" $* *..'2 $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' %$2#$'0+'% #(, )*(./+)$ $2#(%.*23#$+*( +( $"' /*(0�$'23� � &*$$*3�9�� �#2$+)+�#$*27 #��2*#)" �9$% )*339(+$+'% #(, $"*%' *( $"' .2*($ /+(' #(, 2')'+6+(0 '(, *. 6+*/'($ )*(./+)$ #$ $"' 6'27 )'($2' *. $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)'� �% #209',� # %+0(+.+)#($ )*($2+&9$+*( *. %9)" #( #��2*#)" +% +$% )#�#)+$7 $* 0'$ $* $"' (+$$7�02+$$7 *. +($2#�)*339(+$7 )*(./+)$� 9(,'2%$#(, $"' �!; !� �''� .*2 '<#3�/'� �� �*/%$*( #(, :� �)2#$*(� - ( $"' �9// 8/#2' *. �(0/+%" :*/+$+)%1 A����B =� +���� *� � $���� �=C �=� #$ ���� != �� �$#(/'7� -�29$" �*33+%%+*(% #(, $"' �')*0(+$+*( *. �$#$' �2+3'1 A����B =� +���� *� � $���� ��� !C� � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/ /*)#/ ,7(#3+)%� )2'#$' ,+#/*09'� #(, &' )*($'<$�%�')+.+)� 8+6'( #��2*�2+#$' 2'%*92)'%� %9)" +(+$+#$+6'% "#6' $"' �*$'($+#/ $* %$+39/#$' %*)+'$7�4+,' ,+#/*09'� %*3'$"+(0 4"+)" +% 9%9#//7 #$$2+&9$', $* *..+)+#/ -$29$"�$'//+(01 �2*)'%%'%� ( 0'('2#/� "*4'6'2� $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' ,+%)*92%' "#% $'(,', $* 9(,'26#/9' # &*$$*3�9�� �#2$+)+�#$*27 #��2*#)" #(, +$ 2'3#+(% /#20'/7 9(,'2� $"'*2+F', #(, 9(,'2�2'%'#2)"',� �"'2' #2' 9(,'(+#&/7 # 2#(0' *. ,+..+)9/$ )"#//'(0'% +(6*/6', +( #$$'3�$+(0 $* �2*3*$' #(, '%$#&/+%" /*)#//7 *4(', �#2$+)+�#$*27 $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' #��2*#)"'%� �"'2' #2' 6#/+, G9'%$+*(% #2*9(, 4"* $"' /*)#/% #2'� 4"* %�'#5% .*2 4"*3� #(, 4"#$ '<#)$/7 ,*'% /*)#/ *4('2%"+� #(, �#2$+)+�#$+*( 3'#(J �*2 +% $"' 4"*/'%#/' 6#/*2+F#$+*( *. -+(%+,'2%1 $* $"' '<)/9%+*( *. -*9$%+,'2%1 '+$"'2 # %9%$#+(#&/' *2 ,'%+2#&/' #��2*#)"� H*4� $**� )#( �2*�*� ('($% *. �#2$+)+�#$*27 #��2*#)"'% '(%92' $"#$ $"'7 ,* (*$ &')*3' 3'2' 4+(,*4 ,2'%%+(0� *2 # 3'#(% $* +()9/)#$' '<$'2(#/ +,'*/*0+)#/ �2*E')$% 9(,'2 $"' 09+%' *. /*)#/ )*($2*/J �"' )*(9(,293 9/$+3#$'/7 +% *(' )*33*( $* # 2#(0' *. *$"'2 .+'/,%I "*4 $* )*3&+(' $"' �*$'($+#//7 /#9,#&/' '(,% *. # 0/*&#/ "93#( 2+0"$% )9/$92' 4+$"*9$ $"' 3'#(% *. $"'+2 +($2*,9)$+*( #)$+(0 #% $"' ('0#$+*( *. $"*%' 6'27 2+0"$%� �'6'2$"'/'%%� #% $"' %�"'2' *. $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' #��'#2 $* 3*6' '6'2 3*2' 4+,'/7 *9$ +($* $"' 2'#/3 *. '(0'(,'2+(0 %*)+#/ #(, �*/+$+)#/ )"#(0'� $"'( $"' �2+6+/'0+(0 *. *..+)+#/ #0'()+'%� +($'2(#$+*(#/ +(%$+$9$+*(%� $"' /#4 #(, /'0#/ -'<�'2$+%'1 *6'2 #(, #&*6' /*)#//7 0'('2#$', '3&',,', +(+$+#$+6'% 39%$ &' &2*90"$ +()2'#%+(0/7 +($* G9'%$+*(� �( *&6+*9% %*92)' $* +(.*23 %9)" # 2'$"+(5� #% 4' ,+%)*6'2', *92%'/6'% +( )#227+(0 *9$ 4*25 +( �*2$"'2( 2'/#(,� +% 2'#,+/7 #6#+/#&/'� . $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' +% $* $#5' �#2$+)+�#$+*( %'2+*9%/7 $"'( �'2"#�% # 0**, %$#2$+(0 �/#)' +% $* +,'($+.7 %*3' *. $"' 5'7 09+,+(0 �2+()+�/'% $"#$ "#6' &''( %+0(#//', +( $"' %9&%$#($+#/ /+$'2#$92'� '<�'2+'()'� #(, %$*)5 *. 5(*4/',0' ,'2+6', .2*3 ,'6'/*�3'($ #(, �#2$+)+� �#$*27 $"'*27 #(, �2#)$+)'� �"'2' +% # ('', $* .*%$'2 #0'()7 &7 $"+(5+(0 +3#0+(#$+6'/7 *9$%+,' $"' -�2'6#+/+(0 $2#(%+$+*(#/ E9%$+)' &*<1� H*4'6'2� $"' .+2%$ %$'� $* ,'6'/*�+(0 %$2#$'0+'% +% $* )2'#$' %�#)'% .*2 �'*�/' $* ,'$'23+('� %"#�'� #(, ,'6'/*� %*/9$+*(% .*2 $"'3%'/6'%� �!� � ���� �"' �9$"*2� �*92(#/ �*3�+/#$+*( � ���� �#2,+.. �(+6'2%+$7 �#4 �)"**/ work_lv3jsej6qng35gg6od7jcvet4i ---- 1 Forgiveness as Potentiality in Criminal Justice Aaron Pycroft University of Portsmouth UK Clemens Bartollas University of Northern Iowa Abstract To explore the problematic of forgiveness in criminal justice we argue for and utilise the deep homologies that exist between the continental philosophical tradition and approaches to complexity theory (the potential to realise new dynamical states). Through taking a hermeneutical narrative approach we argue that studied together they provide us with new insights into questions of punishment, retribution and rehabilitation and enable us to better understand the connections that exist between victims of crime, perpetrators and the community through examination of the content of dominant narratives that emerge in the historical relationship between theology and law; gain insight into an increased path lock (entropic justice) with respect to retribution in liberal democracies such as the USA and UK based upon decomposition of the Judaeo-Christian message; and examine what contemporary stories of forgiveness reveal with respect to accessing new dynamical states and new ways of doing justice that challenge dominant and reductionist narrative. Introduction In examining the concept of forgiveness we do so with some trepidation and conscious of Spinoza’s dictum that all determination is negation (see e.g. Melamed, 2012) i.e. the more that we examine the concept and seek to reduce it to component parts the less we are able to say what it is; it is an irreducible concept. Different methods are required then to explore the elusive problematic of forgiveness in criminal justice and to achieve this we tentatively seek to argue for and utilise the deep homologies that exist between the continental philosophical tradition and approaches to complexity theory. Our approach is one of hermeneutical narrative in which we seek to bring new resources to our criminological perspective through occupying liminal spaces and “Where one tries to get one’s bearings as 2 one transits between two (or more) worlds” (Kearney, 2011: xvii). This process is always uncertain, un-finalizable and inevitably partial and therefore difficult but we seek to engage with diverse thinkers and traditions who have the potential to offer significant insights to criminology and the practices of justice to further important dialogue. We argue for a conceptualisation of forgiveness as an expression of multiplicity in unity (it is more than the sum of its parts) and which is rooted in the irreducible and emergent relationships between the victim, the perpetrator and wider society and to argue therefore that it is not possible to tell one exclusive story (dominant narrative) about forgiveness; to reduce our explanatory perspective to one of either victim, perpetrator or community is to decompose the system. We argue that this approach enables us to: (1) understand the connections that exist between these actors through the content of dominant narrative that emerges in the historical relationship between theology and law (2) gain insight into an increased path lock (entropic justice) with respect to retribution in liberal democracies such as the USA and UK based upon decomposition of the Judaeo-Christian message and (3) examine what contemporary stories1 of forgiveness reveal with respect to accessing new dynamical states and new ways of doing justice that challenge that dominant and reductionist narrative. Both forgiveness and retribution imply the creation of a new moral community informed by but not anchored in the past (Verdeja, 2004:39) but we argue for a new teleological perspective in criminology which addresses the importance of the arrow of time, past, present and future and which avoids a collapse into utilitarian pragmatism2. This teleological 1 We take narrative to imply the “top down” need for control and stories as the “bottom up” demand for ethics (see Verdeja, 2004). 2 The Utilitarian concepts of less eligibility (see Sieh, 1989) and risk management render the future unrealizable through a closing down of opportunity and potential through the removal of resources that would allow for 3 perspective is grounded in choice which is implicitly and explicitly ethical. This choice is then the potential for the creation of a new and positive virtual image of perpetrators of crime that can be projected and actualised in a telos of now. We argue that forgiveness is the dynamic and emergent space onto which these identities are projected in and through time. Our approach is to argue that forgiveness cannot be amnesia but rather that allows for the past (the crime itself and its impact), the present (the practices of justice) and the future (the potential of becoming) to be revealed3. We re-examine foundational Christian texts in the light of developments in both hermeneutical approaches to complexity theory and continental philosophy to provide examples of forgiveness that challenge instrumentalism at the service of final, entropic categories of justice which undermine (by an effective closing down) the possibilities of becoming and the accessing of new dynamical states for victims, perpetrators and communities. Continental philosophy, hermeneutics and complexity theory We take continental philosophy as different from analytic philosophy and rejecting of the latter’s emphases on positivist and empiricist perspectives4. Whilst the continuities and discontinuities of these two traditions are much debated we use Critchley’s argument the potential to access new dynamical states. This is entropic and self-defeating practice as it contains an essential nihilism in that firstly it assumes the rationality of individual actors and therefore the collective calculus of the greatest happiness for the greatest number to be correct, even presumably in the justification of collective violence; but secondly because we cannot say with any certainty in the face of human passions (proclaimed as justified and requiring of satisfaction) precisely where, what or when the end is that truly justifies the means. This problem of the entropic nature of utilitarian eschatology is stated by Nelson (Nelson, 1991: 339) when he says that utilitarianism “Implies a surprising prediction about the future, viz, that all experience of pleasure and pain must end once and for all, or infinitely dwindle.” 3 This approach also rejects dialectical method (the negation of the negation) whereby the past is synthetically dissolved in the creation of a new reality. Complexity theory demonstrates that all complex systems are historical systems that influence the present (see below). 4 See Arrigo and Williams (2014) on the relationships between complexity theory, continental philosophy and Psychological Jurisprudence in criminology 4 (Critchley, 1997:355) that the continental tradition “…takes the form of a critical (emphasis in the original) confrontation with the history of philosophy…with…a critical dismantling of the tradition in terms of what has been unthought and what remains to be thought.” Critchley (Critchley, 1997: 356) argues that this leads to “the demand for a transformative practice of philosophy, art, poetry or thinking…that would be capable of addressing, criticizing and ultimately redeeming the present.” With respect to this continental tradition and the philosophy of complexity theory Paul Cilliers (Cilliers, 1998, 2005) argues that both deconstruction and complexity reveals both the limits of our knowledge and the irreducibility of meaning but in a non-relativistic way5. This limitation is brought about because we inhabit the systems that we study and therefore we can have no absolute and objective knowledge of our lived experience. Meaning and knowledge is contingent and contextual and because it cannot be represented and the context is not transparent we have to choose our hermeneutical frameworks but ultimately “A radical ‘undecidability’ surrounds all signification; there can be no absolute origin or site of meeting.” (Kearney and Rainwater, 1996:439). It is due to this choice, Cilliers argues that we cannot escape what is ethical or normative. Christian scriptures are key texts that have had a dominant but contradictory hegemony (or in the Derridan sense of instability of signs) and importantly in the development of the modern state and apparatus of justice. These historical transformations (bifurcations) are demonstrated through the evolution of resources that are foundational to a Jewish sect committed to radical forgiveness and non-violence through time becoming a justification for 5 It is beyond the scope of this paper to discuss the existence of absolutes in the platonic sense and as utilized in scientific method but see Pycroft (forthcoming) for a discussion of the relationships between phenomenology, complexity theory and criminology 5 punishment and retribution; so much so that the use of these non-violent resources are now controversial in for example restorative justice due to their perceived retributive nature (see Johnstone and Ness, 2007) and religion and punitive ideology would seem to be strongly correlated (e.g. see Baker and Booth, 2016). A hermeneutical approach as a development of continental philosophy helps us to re-examine these texts within the context of their traditions and the hermeneutical circles that are created through those traditions that identify the core texts which are then used to legitimate their activities (see Pellauer and Dauenhauer, 2016). In utilizing insights from hermeneutics we will follow the work of Paul Ricoeur in advancing from a hermeneutic of suspicion to one of affirmation (see Kearney, 1986). Complexity theory itself divides along traditional ontological, epistemological and methodological lines in science, social science and social theory with debates examining the relationships between mathematically deterministic and constructionist approaches (see Pycroft and Bartollas, 2014). However broadly speaking complexity theory in its non- reductionist (whole systems6) approach contrasts to the Newtonian paradigm and its positivist (and analytical philosophical) assumptions enshrined in criminal justice and reflects the argument of Milovanovic (Milovanovic, 2014) that approaches to criminal justice grounded in Newtonian thinking and method are lacking in any bone fide statement on human agency. Complexity theory demonstrates that all systems such as justice systems are driven from the bottom up, by lower order interactions from which the whole system emerges. To understand the nature and behaviour of complex systems reductionist and 6 The language of whole systems can be ethically problematic. We use it as a contrast to the reductionism inherent in positivism and in the sense that Levinas would distinguish between totalizers and infinitizers; with the former being satisfied with themselves and the systems they can organize and control and the latter being dissatisfied and who strive for what is other than themselves (see Levinas, 1969) 6 positivist experimental methodologies reified by positivist approaches are ineffective, as when we abstract from the whole to the part, we can only understand the part and not the whole. We are interested to take an approach which rather than reducing and separating component parts in the practice of justice (e.g. prioritizing retributive passions and the demand of justice on the part of victims and communities or asserting the primacy of rehabilitation in reducing crime) look to the ways in which they interact together and co- constitute each other. Complex systems allow us to confront history as they are historical systems with a memory and which we are constitutive of. We look then to a post Newtonian (post-positivist) account of justice based upon an ontological and epistemological understanding of conjunction (connectionism and emergence) rather than disjunction (reductionism and closing off). As Bartollas (Bartollas, 2014:276) argues: A post-positivist understanding sees community as an extension of neither individualism nor collectivism. The intrinsic nature of community, according to a post-positivist’s view, denies the notion that individuals profit by serving themselves or that individuals can only define themselves through a collective movement. Fostering community does not require participants to lose themselves, but to join with others to become more than themselves.7 These non-totalising perspectives recognise the heterogeneity of the whole system that allows for new dynamical spaces to be created which may challenge the dominant 7 Our approach is consistent with Peacemaking Criminology which to quote Hal Pepinksy (Pepinksy, 2013:320) is concerned with “How to transform violence into cooperation, of how to make peace from the intrapersonal to global levels... (building)… on literature from all manner of sources…most of which is by folks who do not call themselves criminologists either… and a concern for understanding how to transform violence transcends normal academic boundaries.” Our approach is also consistent with Pepinsky’s argument (2013) that Peacemaking Criminology also understands that in crime and criminality there is no political neutrality and that people are locked in set agendas; that stories are data for understanding the social construction of crime; that you cannot impose peacemaking; that peacemaking acts as an attractor (see below) spawning empathy and compassion; outcomes from peacemaking are very uncertain with results not always known. 7 (deterministic) narratives of justice from the bottom up and through an open ended commitment to the enhancement of non-linearity in the forms of uncertainty, undecidability and unfinalizability. Forgiveness is exemplary of non-linearity as it is not proportionate to a crime committed, cannot be required, and may be unlooked for (by victims, perpetrators and communities). The following principles of complexity theory are most significant for our discussion in relation to forgiveness (for a full discussion of the principles in themselves see Pycroft and Bartollas, 2014; Arrigo and Barrett, 2008; Byrne, 1998; Cilliers, 1998) and we argue demonstrate the ways in which history (1) potentially becomes locked into particular narratives but also (2) allows for the creation of new possibilities and dynamical states. The Arrow of Time Due to being open systems complex systems such as justice systems are subject to the arrow to time. A key feature of Newtonian mechanics is that time is reversible whereas complexity theory demonstrates that this is not the case, that the material causes of the past cannot be changed because systems are constantly in evolutionary flux, and moving forward. Our concern is with the ways in which time and the problem of irreversibility is experienced by victims, perpetrators and wider society. Bergson (Bergson, 1971, 1988) argues that the past cannot be changed but its virtual dimensions can be. This is expressed by Žižek (Žižek, 2011: 28) as “When something radically new emerges it retroactively creates its own possibility, its own causes or conditions. A potentiality can be inserted into (or withdrawn from) past reality.” The arrow of time is central to discussions on forgiveness as the material past cannot be changed (Arendt, 1958) but the emergent (transcendent/virtual) properties inherent 8 within complex systems allow us to address those issues because the whole is always more than the sum of its parts. Iteration and path dependence Modern justice systems are founded and grounded in features and functions that have founding myths and including in the practice of rehabilitation. Historical practice has woven together the exercise of utilitarian power (myths of rationality and social contract giving rise to concepts of less eligibility and risk assessment) alongside the explicitly theological language of rehabilitation (the virtues of hope and making good focusing on pro-social attitudes to access social capital). As Hathaway (Hathaway, 2003) argues it is impossible to understand the law as it is practiced now without understanding the law as it has been practiced in the past. Hathaway in examining the role of history in law highlights the importance of tradition in constitutional interpretation, the role of historical narrative in decision making and the value of precedent. Furthermore advances in complexity theory demonstrate the nature of cultural and organizational path dependence with Sydow et al (Sydow et al, 2009) arguing that the process has the following properties: that outcomes are unpredictable and indeterminate; that several outcomes are possible and that history selects from the alternatives; trapped actors cannot shift the patterns once established; the path lock eventually leads to inferior and sub optimal outcomes (entropy). So with respect to the practices of criminal justice we would argue that an overt focus on retribution and punishment is not the only possible outcome from the interaction of processes under consideration, but we need to understand how this path lock has emerged and how it can be shifted. To use the language of Deleuze and Guattari (see Massumi, 1996) punishment in the forms of retribution and incarceration has reached a plateau of intensity that is not 9 automatically dissipated in a climax leading to a state of rest. In practice there is a heightening of energies which are sustained and dynamic enough to appropriate from each other and weave together to form any number of different reinforcing connections. Sensitivity to initial conditions and bifurcations Very small changes in the lower order interactions of a complex system can have a massive impact on the system overall. These are the emergent properties of the system which cannot be predicted or mapped mathematically as it is always more than the sum of its parts (transcendent properties). These small changes may lead to changes in the trajectory of the system and the accessing of new dynamical states. The development of the Jewish sect that became Christianity and its influence on the development of modern states and (amongst other things) justice systems are examples of this that we discuss below. What becomes evident is precisely the instability of Christian8 signs of forgiveness across history and the ways in which they can become appropriated and subverted to very different ends. Attractor states Attractors are like magnets that pull/push systems in particular directions in time and space and which exhibit regularities and apparent patterns of stability (chaotic, edge of chaos and equilibrium). Due to its highly mathematical nature attractor theory (see Guastello and Liebovitch, 2009) has been contentious in postmodern conceptions of complexity with for example Cilliers (Cilliers, 1998) arguing that they are another aspect of reductionism that do 8 Our focus is on Judeo-Christian theology as being foundational to modern western societies and legal systems, however we also acknowledge the importance of Islamic culture and science to that development from the 7th Century CE onwards, not least in rediscovery of ancient Greek philosophy through the work of Ibn Sīnā which did much to invigorate scholastic thought; Thomas Aquinas referred to him as “The Commentator.” The contribution of Islamic thought to understandings of forgiveness and its relationship to Christianity and western culture is an important area for development and research. See Menocal (2002). 10 not sufficiently address aspects of the whole system. However within hermeneutics and social theory there has been an interest in strange attractors (for example in the work of Deleuze and Guattari (see Massumi, 1996). A strange (sometimes called chaotic) attractor is one in which there are patterns and regularities but the system never follows the same trajectory (see Pycroft, 2014). There are processes of both expansion and contraction and the chaotic motion operates in more than one dimension. There is order and control although each order parameter is affected by the behaviour of other order parameters. These attractors are prone to bifurcate, that is become increasingly complex by accessing new dynamical states in their environment; this is effect and effect rather than cause and effect. This makes the evolution of the whole system and its trajectories fundamentally uncertain. Hermeneutically strange attractors are examples of qualitative multiplicities, containing infinite possibilities that are not foreseeable, with the realisation of the possible only existing in retrospect. This then allows for understanding the divergence and convergence and complexity of human lived experience grounded in relational time. Girard’s (e.g. Girard, 1978, 1999) scapegoating thesis is highly compatible with complexity and attractor theory as his approach charts the ways in which groups, communities, societies achieve equilibrium through the scapegoating mechanism: Faced with some crisis (chaos) the use of violence against the apparent perpetrator of the crisis (edge of chaos) restores equilibrium to the community. Scapegoating serves as a fundamental cultural attractor that arises from our evolutionary inheritance. Girard’s is a theory grounded in the mimetic nature of desire and human passions. His idea is that in desiring what others have then we model ourselves on those people who then become our rivals, and which leads to periodic outbreaks of mimetic violence; this violence is constrained in unequal societies but particularly comes 11 to the fore when dominant groups find themselves in positions of economic and social equality with minority groups. With respect to criminal justice the Girardian perspective helps us to further understand the locking in of revenge and retribution: For example with respect to victims and perpetrators under the justice model once punishment is completed the perpetrator is now innocent and justly expectant of the rights and resources of society to be restored or given to them. However it is this that brings about a mimetic crisis leading to the scapegoating of ex-offenders who for legal purposes are now innocent. The form that this scapegoating takes is enshrined in utilitarian teleology (the concepts of less eligibility and risk managements and reinforced by satisfaction theory (discussed below) by maintaining that the violence inherent in the continued denunciation by the community ostensibly in support of the original victim is justified over and above the rights of the person who has served their punishment on the basis of the further risks that they might present and the necessity of a deterrent effect. Dissipative structures Forgiveness and its relationship to the energy of human passions within criminal justice has been discussed by Murphy and Hampton (Murphy and Hampton, 1988) and Lacey and Pickard (Lacey and Pickard, 2015) whereby the desire for justice on the part of victims and communities are used to reinforce punitive models of justice. Energy is the key analogy in complex systems (see Pycroft, 2014; Byrne, 1998) and complex systems are open systems constantly interacting with their environment to gain new energy, to enhance that energy and then to dissipate it back into the environment. At times the environment may deprive the system of energy or overload it thus driving change (Byrne and Callaghan, 2014) by providing critical levels of disorder which not only (potentially) break down but also allow for 12 spontaneous and novel forms of re-organization (Williams and Arrigo, 2002). In our argument and in terms of radical and transformative justice we can utilize Bergson’s (Bergson, 1988) development of Aristotle’s conception of potentiality (dunamis) and its relationship to actuality (energeia) which rather than being concerned with someone’s power to produce a change (e.g. to make good through voluntary contrition, or to impose punishment to coerce contrition) is their capacity to be in a different and more completed state (Cohen, 2016) and enabled to be so through the actions of both the victim and the community. Forgiveness Having established our approach we now look to developments in the study of the concept of forgiveness itself. A main focus of studies in forgiveness have been theological but perhaps due to a resurgence in interest in Aristotelian virtue ethics (e.g. Anscombe, 1958) had also seen increased philosophical interest in the late 20th Century9 (e.g. Kolnai, 1974, Downie, 1965). It was Griswold’s work (Griswold, 2007) that challenged the Judaeo-Christian hegemony in debates on forgiveness by re-examining Greek and Roman sources. However a re-examination of these debates particularly with respect to the person and theology of St Paul10 demonstrates some interesting and challenging perspectives. The secular Jewish philosopher Hannah Arendt argued that Jesus of Nazareth discovered the role of forgiveness in human affairs (Arendt, 1958) however this is challenged by Griswold (Griswold, 2007) who argues that she overstates the case as he finds significant evidence for concepts of forgiveness already existing in pre-Christian Greco-Roman culture. The ancient 9 There has been significant interest in criminal justice e.g. in the development of Psychological Jurisprudence (see Arrigo and Williams, 2014)) and also the Good Lives Model (Ward and Maruna, 2007) 10 The person and theology of St Paul has become a key area of scholarship in continental philosophy; see e.g. Badiou (2003); Breton (2011); Azzam (2015); Kearney (2016). 13 Greeks did not have a word for forgiveness; Aristotle used a range of words associated with the verb sungignosko relating to think with, agree with, recognize; all are linked with notions of relationship and empathy (see Griswold, 2007). However for Aristotle forgiveness is neither a virtue or religiously based but rather it is linked to civic politics (see Bash, 2014). The key is to be found in Aristotle’s concept of unbearable circumstance (Aristotle, 2004) which is linked to a perfectionist ethical stance linked to external forces. The virtuous, detached and rational man does not make mistakes and can be excused for events outside of his control, hence no forgiveness is required. But importantly any sense of empathy does not extend to un-virtuous persons and the irrationality of the “mob.” Bash (Bash, 2014) highlights that within the New Testament there are differences between the Gospels and the Pauline epistles concerning the nature of forgiveness. Both Jesus of Nazareth and Paul of Tarsus challenge the link between ritual conceptions of purity, sin and forgiveness and both argue that there is an injunction on Christians to forgive. However in the Synoptic Gospels there is an emphasis by Jesus on interpersonal forgiveness, whereby repentance is necessary to be forgiven by God, but likewise to be forgiven it is necessary to forgive others, as in the following (the Hebrew verb used is Aphiemi which has a legal connotation of acquitting, a sense of release, to excuse and cancel a debt): “Then Peter went up to him and said ‘Lord, how often must I forgive my brother if he wrongs me? As often as seven times?” Jesus answered, ‘Not seven I tell you, but seventy-seven times.” (Matthew 18 verses 21-22, New Jerusalem Bible: 1130): In contrast the point is made by Bash (Bash, 2015) that Paul of Tarsus whose epistles constitute a significant proportion of the New Testament is not a theologian of forgiveness (he rarely mentions the word) but one of justification and by justification he means a gift of 14 grace to undeserving people. This is interesting because despite Paul being a Hellenised Jew with the expectation that he would use sungignosko type concepts he actually uses the Hebrew charizmoi to express gifts of grace (Bash, 2014). In this sense rather than the requirements of the gospels to be forgiven through forgiving, it would seem that Paul in arguing that a justified people are a forgiven people and that even the desire to repent is as a consequence of a gift of grace, is arguing for the community to forgive as an act and expression of grace. The Pauline approach is in part a reflection of Paul’s own experience (see also Breton, 2011). He had been a persecutor of the early Jews who joined the emerging Christian church and he was complicit in the stoning to death of Stephen a Christian disciple and which seems to have led to Paul’s conversion to Christianity (Acts Chapters 7-9). In Acts the story goes on to show how afraid the people were of Paul after his sudden conversion, including the leaders of the church, but when another Apostle named Barnabas (and interestingly the name Bar-Nabas is translated as both Son of Encouragement and Son of Consolation) advocated for him, he was accepted (Acts 9 vv 26-30) hesitantly into the community of Christians but went on to become the key Apostle to the Gentiles, promulgating Christianity throughout the Middle and Near East. A reading of the Pauline story reveals especially the conversion “Event” (see Badiou, 1986) is instructive as at no point was he asked to repent, or humiliate himself before the community, neither was he required to make atonement so that the community were satisfied as to his intentions. But equally as importantly Paul did not try to hide or to justify his past and we can infer from the text that his past was a key component in the emergence of a new identity (Saul becomes Paul). In this experience (Acts 9 vv1-7) he is only asked one question by Jesus “Saul, Saul why do you persecute me?” to which the only response that Saul 15 has is to ask who is speaking to him, and to which Jesus responds with his name and to tell Saul to follow the directions given to him. His new identify is a gift rather than something earned. This idea of gift stands in stark contrast to contemporaneous practices of justice and the Authentic Apology Model (Allan, 2008) which enshrines a functionalist approach to the forgiveness of a perpetrator of a crime or a civic offence with the onus on the wrong doer to explain their wrongful behaviour and to accept liability; to experience an emotional response to the wrong and to action behaviour to right the wrongs done. Allan (Allan, 2008) in asserting this approach argues that criminal law and punishment is fundamental to social order and equilibrium and reinforces those processes through also deterrence and offering the possibility of rehabilitation. For Allan apology is central to the process of rehabilitation by allowing the wrongdoer to humiliate themselves and to show respect to victims and society and therefore demonstrate that they are not of bad character. Atonement and social order – a hermeneutic of suspicion Hermeneutics and the work of Ricoeur helps us to examine the relationships between ideology and religion and the ways in which an “Ideological recollection of sacred foundational acts has the purpose …of integrating and justifying a social order” (Kearney, 1986:112) and to address the question of how in societies whose cultural identity is rooted in the Judaeo-Christian tradition we have moved from these radical, creative and radically reinforcing stories of forgiveness and grace to those of a dominant, locked and dampening narrative of conditionality; and whereby the original meanings of these texts are obscured to the extent that for examples within debates on restorative justice forgiveness is controversial and perhaps lacks an articulation of meaning and philosophical resources (see Armour and 16 Umbreit, 2005)? Ricoeur’s hermeneutic of suspicion seeks to recover repressed meanings. A key factor in the repression of original meanings was the historical convergence of Christian theological notions of forgiveness becoming inextricably linked with theories of atonement. Prior to Anselm of Canterbury (1033-1109) a Christus Victor theology saw mankind as being in bondage and held hostage to the evil powers of Sin, Death and the Devil. This is not dissimilar to Aristotle’s idea of unbearable circumstances however under this human focussed theology (see Eddy and Beilby, 2006) Christ frees mankind from those circumstances irrespective of their purity or rationality (Aulen, 2010). Aulen (2010) argues that this theology was rich in imagery and metaphor but was displaced by a more ‘rational’, approach based on satisfaction theory. Satisfaction theory is Godward looking (Eddy and Beilby, 2006) and argues that the justification for punishment and retribution is that God Himself is punitive and demands satisfaction through sacrifice and punishment for every sin so as to make atonement. These fundamental changes (bifurcation) in theological thinking coincide with the rediscovery of Greek philosophy by Islamic and Christian Scholastics; hence the Aristotelian influence of purity and elitism becomes apparent. This idea had also been reinforced by Augustine’s earlier Platonic ideas in the City of God (Augustine, 1958) that the State is a bulwark against sin. In this historical development and in seeking to understand why liberal democracies that have had a Christian identity are so punitive in their approaches to criminal justice, contra biblical accounts of forgiveness Gorringe (Gorringe, 1996) argues that religion and law are related at the deepest level and that, “Christian theology constituted the most potent form of ideology in western society for at least a thousand years up to the 18th/19th centuries and its ideological importance is by no means dead. It was both influenced by, and influenced, penal thinking. It represented a 17 construal of the crucifixion of Christ, by no means inevitable, which reinforced retributive thinking, according to which sin or crimes have to be punished and cannot be dealt with in any other way.” Gorringe argues that satisfaction theory emerged in the 11th century at the same time as criminal law took shape, and reacted on each other with theology drawing on legal notions and law looking for metaphysical justification. The contrast between the two approaches is significant as in Satisfaction Theory Christ is the only acceptable sacrifice to an angry God who demands retribution, whereas Christus Victor is a freely given act of love from God, in the face of unbearable circumstances for mankind e.g. “the gift of grace expressed in the Pauline letters, and the cross of Christ is not a justification of punishment but a heralding of its end” (Gorringe, 1996: 269). The rediscovery of Greek philosophy by the medieval Scholastics may have provided a framework for establishing a purely rational theology but in so doing discarded the dramatic symbolism of classical atonement. Thus, perhaps unwittingly a theology of difference and individualisation that reinstated a Greek view of unbearable circumstances and purity alongside Christian notions of sin, penance and satisfaction was introduced that negated the Biblical view of the powerlessness of Everyman and the need for outside and freely given help (grace). This philosophically informed approach to theology has been essential to the creation of a hegemonic and state sponsored Christian religion, fundamental to social order, and therefore complicit in cruelty , punishment and the exercise of power. It is argued by Martin (Martin, 2014:42) that: “It is not in the least surprising that Christianity devised strategies of negotiation, compromise and assimilation as it spread in societies characterised by discourses of power and codes of 18 honour. On the contrary, the history of Christianity…follows precisely the course you would expect…the presentation of Christianity was often loaded towards the Old Testament, so that rulers fashioned their self-understanding in the image of Solomon, David, Hezekiah or Josiah. Appropriations of the figure of Christ crucified by monarchs and ecclesiastics were much less popular because less plausible and persuasive, except when deployed at tangents that ignored the stripping away of the human dignity of Christ by the legally constituted authorities in ‘Church’ and state. The Godly Prince of the Renaissance ruling jure divino found scant gratification in the role of a convicted felon.” Girard (Girard, 1978) along with Nietzsche (Nietzsche, 2003, 2008) and Foucault (Foucault, 1975) is concerned with the ways in which cruelty is linked to the exercise of power and ideology. It is clear that violent interpretation (or rather subversion) of scriptural texts are used to justify violence and punishment. So whereas Foucault focuses on disciplinary technologies and normative social science that expel the old rituals of violent expiation, Nietzsche and Girard find evidence of those continued mechanisms which are revealed through myths and literature, ancient and modern. The meeting of the thought of Nietzsche and Girard are we argue the key fault lines in understanding the relationship between collective violence, social order and religion. For Girard the Judeo-Christian tradition and gospels reveal a genuine epistemology of love, forgiveness and non-violence, whereas for Nietzsche at best they reinforce the links between religion and justified violence. Girard argues (Girard, 1978, 2008) that scapegoat rituals are the process by which violence is contained and resolved in societies and is linked with religious rituals. Girard identifies the scapegoat mechanism as being behind every ritual including those of justice, punishment and denunciation (Girard 1978). Likewise Dupuy (Dupuy, 2013) observes that with the decline of 19 the twin pillars of religion and monarchy justice is the only publicly ubiquitous ritual that advanced industrial countries have left. What is significant and controversial about Girard’s theory and what differs from traditional anthropological accounts of scapegoating (e.g. Frazier, 1922) is his psycho-analytically informed argument that scapegoating should not be seen as a conscious activity based on a conscious choice. The process is effective precisely because there is an element of delusion to which we are all susceptible, so all of us can condemn examples of scapegoating yet none of us can identify our own involvement in it. Girard (Girard, 2008) argues that the scapegoat is a coherent enough interpretation of all rituals that resemble the Leviticus ritual. In the Mosaic ritual of the Day of Atonement (Leviticus 16) the scapegoat is that one of the two goats chosen by lot to be sent alive into the wilderness, the sins of the people having been symbolically laid upon it, while the other was appointed to be sacrificed. Whether physical or psychological the violence directed at the victim appears to be justified because the scapegoated person has brought about some evil that must be avenged, resisted and oppressed. History and contemporaneous societies are replete with examples and in addressing mimetic violence and social disorder the scapegoat restores order through becoming the focus for retribution and denunciation. A social dimension is always present, with persecutors a majority and their victims a minority and implies a process of displacement or transference and reveals the unconscious dimensions of social order. This is clearly expressed by Jesus who during his crucifixion stated “Father forgive them, they do not know what they are doing.” (Luke 23 v 34); likewise as he is being stoned to death Stephen “…knelt down and said aloud, ‘Lord do not hold this sin against them.” (Acts 7 v 60). Girard (Girard, 2014) argues that in scapegoating the victim is always innocent in the face of the violent collective, and that Christianity has taken the side of innocent victims (for example in the judicial execution of Jesus of Nazareth who was innocent but was the chosen 20 scapegoat to restore social order in a Jerusalem at threat of violent unrest) whereas as Nietzsche for example sees this as nothing more than revenge by the weak against the strong, a Christian slave mentality indicated by forgiveness which in itself was nothing more than a form of revenge (Nietzsche,2008). Girard then reveals much of what has become hidden or obscured in the historical development and practice of Christian narrative. In the words of Richard Kearney (Kearney, 1999:252): “Girard seeks accordingly to make the operations of our social imaginary – i.e. our ideological unconscious – answerable to ethics. He resolves to subject ideologies of scapegoating to a critical hermeneutics of suspicion, exposing concealed meanings behind apparent ones…sacrificial figures though invariably aliens and excoriated by their contemporaries become hallowed over the ages until they are eventually remembered as saviour gods who restored their community from chaos to order. They emerge out of the mists of time as miraculous ‘others’ who managed to transmute conflict into law. But this miraculous alteration of sacrificed ‘aliens’ into sacred ‘others’ is predicated upon a strategic forgetfulness of their original stigmatisation…” Forgiveness, accessing new dynamical states – a hermeneutic of affirmation A hermeneutic of suspicion allows us to revisit texts and messages which have become obscured, subverted and locked in through historical violence and which potentially offers an alternative to that violence. These sources demonstrate that we are all complicit in scapegoating and violence but also offer us the potential for new and creative spaces; a way out of our violence. So in contrast with the current conceptualisation implying that only 21 retribution acknowledges guilt and therefore personal responsibility (and the claim that we are justified and responsible in our retribution) Gorringe (Gorringe, 1996) argues that this is also implicit within any act of forgiveness. He states that this brings about a paradigm shift that has the potential to change the past and the future and therefore perceptions and roles and regulations too and we would add challenge the highly deterministic locking in of retribution to justice systems. This approach fits with De Valve’s argument that justice is what love gives us (De Valve, 2017b:384) that we need new approaches that “must be an individualization that facilitates a full actualization and celebration of the individual, but through the mutual action of the community.” Furthermore in exploring the dynamics of peaceful rebellion he argues (De Valve, 2017a: 98) that justice is a sacrament in the form of an outward and behavioural symbol which is “a boundary-spanning event.” This is St Paul’s conception of grace in action, a hermeneutic of affirmation (see Kearney, 1986) which can be conceptualised and realised in diverse ways: For Gorringe (Gorringe, 1996) forgiveness is a space of a hard fought praxis as demonstrated by the example of Terri Roberts (Roberts with Windle, 2015) and her recounting of her Son Charlie Roberts and his shooting of 10 Amish girls in a school house in Pennsylvania in 2006. Five girls were murdered the others seriously injured and then he killed himself. Immediately following the shooting the Amish Bishop extended forgiveness to the killer. What is remarkable about this account is the ways in which the Amish community including the parents of the killed and injured children reached out to Terri Roberts and her family despite the pain, anguish and grief that they were feeling. Over time it became possible to establish solid relationships both with parents, other members of the community and the surviving 22 children. There is one example from the book that both practically and symbolically represents the movement of the injured individuals and the community towards the perpetrator and his family: Charlie Roberts himself was to be buried with a quiet service in a cemetery away from the town in which he lived and the massacre occurred. The Roberts family were assured by the police of complete privacy and no press intrusion, but as they arrived at the cemetery the media were present in large numbers. However unbeknown to the family the Amish community were also there and they surrounded the family and the burial so that the view for the media was disrupted. Arendt (Arendt, 1961) in discussing the arrow of time argues that both the past and the future are forces which act on the present, and that the person is inserted not into this time but into a gap in time which is kept in existence by a constant fight against past and future. It is in this gap that we can insert new beginnings (natality) by differentiating between time and space; our freedom is dissociated from time and associated with space. Importantly we are not talking here of a timeless, idealised, Platonic space but one that has a spatial dimension (Arendt, 1961) as seen in the following example. Daniel Poskitt’s sister had been murdered by her boyfriend who was convicted and imprisoned. After 10 years they had the opportunity for a victim-offender conference: “We all had the opportunity to talk, to ask questions. “Why did you kill Karen? What were you thinking?” He had no answers for us; he said he didn’t know why he killed her and that he couldn’t remember the details of that day. For our family, this was unacceptable – we had come for answers. My father was angry and I felt angry too. Dad stood up and demanded that he tell us why. A ball of anger formed in the pit of my stomach and forced itself up and out of my mouth. I stood up and shouted: “You fucking coward.” It felt good, really good, to get that 23 anger out after 10 years. I didn’t even know I had it, but I knew after it came out. For me, it was a healing experience. It allowed me to let go of the anger and see the world differently. It didn’t bring back Karen but it did bring me back to a point where I can now forgive him. That may sound strange to some people, but I’ve learnt that forgiveness is not about the perpetrator, it about you. It’s about you letting go of the stuff that holds you back so you can live a happy and fulfilling life.” (http://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2015/nov/03/i-was-able-to-forgive-my- sisters-murderer-only-by-acknowledging-my-own-anger For Bergson (Bergson and Andison, 2010) intuition is a creative leap, and both opposed to platonic reconstitution after analysis, by moving forward rather than looking backwards, but also seeing the possibility of new beginnings (telos), now, rather than at some time in the future. This is demonstrated in the trial of Oscar Groning who was an SS Guard at Auschwitz and who kept records of the belongings that were confiscated from the prisoners when they were brought to the camp. Groning had never denied his guilt but was brought to trial due to a change in the law that allowed for his prosecution. During the trial Eva Kor who had been a prisoner in Auschwitz, and along with Miriam her twin sister had been experimented on by Josef Mengele publicly forgave Groning. After giving her testimony she walked across the court room, shook his hand and embraced him. Afterwards she said that this had not been planned and added: “I wanted to thank him for having some human decency in accepting responsibility for what he has done. I was always interested in meeting him face to face because I believe that there is a human interaction that I cannot predict and no one else can predict.” http://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2015/nov/03/i-was-able-to-forgive-my-sisters-murderer-only-by-acknowledging-my-own-anger http://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2015/nov/03/i-was-able-to-forgive-my-sisters-murderer-only-by-acknowledging-my-own-anger 24 (http://www.theguardian.com/world/2015/apr/27/auschwitz-survivor-angers-plaintiffs- trial-forgiveness) Eva Kor claimed that Groning was so overwhelmed by her unexpected gesture that he fainted. Later she called for prosecutions of SS officers to stop, to allow them to come forward and to explain themselves. In this case we might say that a leap of intuition moved Eva Kor beyond the retributive passions to allow for new and creative possibilities which she argued would encourage other Nazis to come forward and to explain themselves. These new beginnings, praxis and intuition have some self-sympathy for unbearable circumstances and an acknowledgment that crime is both a failing of the individual and the community, and therefore rehabilitation is the responsibility of both the individuals involved and the community. Bergson argues (Bergson, 1988) that normal feelings are caused by a representation of the other, whereas creative feelings create new representations: Our normal feelings for punishment and retribution are caused by the negative representation of the criminal whereas creative feelings grounded in forgiveness create the potential for hope and the projection of a positive image that might be actualized. Practically this means that forgiveness needs to be the starting point of rehabilitation rather than a mythical and elusive end point that in practice can rarely if ever materialize. For Bergson humans express new possibilities by enfolding new layers of habits which challenge and change the solidification and accretions that emerge from our connections with larger surrounding structures; there is a need for periods of in-determination when existing habits and practices are suspended and which allows for creative evolution (Bergson and Andison 2010); importantly we remember how that change has come about, what the change is relative to, however a new situation is actualized. http://www.theguardian.com/world/2015/apr/27/auschwitz-survivor-angers-plaintiffs-trial-forgiveness http://www.theguardian.com/world/2015/apr/27/auschwitz-survivor-angers-plaintiffs-trial-forgiveness 25 Forgiveness is the dynamic space in which this enabled to happen. This does not and cannot take the form of a static, binary, platonic and idealised category (the latter is Derrida’s conception of impossibility) but rather through praxis, natality or intuition it becomes an ethic of choice allowing possibility and potential to emerge from the practice of justice and which is explicitly committed to the past, present and future. Forgiveness is the space that emerges from the community as gift to both victims and perpetrators that: understands that a wrong has been committed and that there are victims and perpetrators; that victims’ experiences are real, potentially traumatic and life changing and who demand justice and the expression of retributive passions; who understand or are prepared to understand their own propensity to violence and complicity in violence; who are prepared to offer a future for both victims and perpetrators for the benefit of the whole community11. Conclusion We have shown how a study of forgiveness can allow for the creation of new beginnings and potentialities for both individuals and society. The barriers to achieving this potentiality are achieved not by limitation and exclusion but only through a real reconceptualization of the new imagination of what is possible; insights into forgiveness that contrast with retributive principles provide such possibilities. The process of new beginnings in part involves a re- reading of foundational texts and myths in the light of new scholarship and research, and that 11 Truth and Reconciliation events around the world have sought to do just that and often through being presided over by a cleric, to varying degrees of success. The most famous being Archbishop Desmond Tutu in South Africa; there was controversy over whether he should wear his episcopal garb and with participants claiming that because of his presence and the symbolism of Christianity that they felt under pressure to forgive (see Brewer, Mitchell and Leavey, 2016) and that there was then something false about the process. Likewise research has shown (Colvin, 2000) that perhaps unsurprisingly reconciliation means different things to different people but that there was a perception that perpetrators of crime were being rewarded by the system in the form of amnesties and continued pensions but that the victims were still suffering the effects of apartheid and its atrocities. To stress the point forgiveness cannot be required but given the right conditions can be allowed to emerge over time. 26 inform new methodologies and practices in doing justice. However in opening up new spaces for doing justice then we need to be cognizant of the historically determined factors that explain where we are now and a criminological hermeneutic that is informed by complexity theory and continental philosophy allows us to achieve this. Acknowledgements We would like to thank peer reviewers of earlier versions of this paper and also advice, comments and discussion from Prof Bruce Arrigo, Prof Anthony Bash and Father James Alison and Prof Andrew Millie. The paper was also the basis of presentations at the British Society of Criminology Annual Conference at Plymouth University and also the European Conference on Ethics, Religion and Philosophy (both in 2015) and we are indebted for the contributions from participants. Bibliography Allan, A. (2008) ‘Functional Apologies in Law’ in Psychiatry, Psychology and Law Vol.15(3): 369-381 Anscombe, E. (1958) ‘Modern Moral Philosophy’ in Philosophy Vol. 33(124): 1-19 Arendt, H. (1958) The Human Condition. Chicago. University of Chicago Press. Arendt, H. (1961) Between Past and Future: Eight Exercises in Political Thought. New York. Vikin381 Aristotle (2004). The Nichomachean Ethics. London. Penguin Books Armour, M. and Umbreit, M. (2005) ‘The paradox of forgiveness in restorative justice’ in E. Worthington The Handbook of Forgiveness. New York. Routledge: 491-504 Arrigo, B. and Barrett, L. (2008) ‘Philosophical Criminology and Complex Systems Science: Towards a Critical Theory of Justice’ in Critical Criminology 16: 165-184 Arrigo, B. and Williams, C. (2014) ‘Complexity, law and ethics: On drug addiction, natural recovery and the diagnostics of psychological jurisprudence’ in Pycroft, A and Bartollas, C 27 (eds) Applying Complexity Theory: Whole systems approaches to criminal justice and social work. Bristol. Policy Press: 247-268 Augustine, St. (1958) City of God. London. Penguin Books. Aulen, G. (2003) Christus Victor: An Historical Study of the Three Main Types of the Idea of Atonement. Wipf & Stock Publishers Azzam, A. (2015). Nietzsche versus Paul. New York. Columbia University Press Badiou, P. (2003). St Paul: The foundation of universalism. Stanford. Stanford University Press. Baker, J. and Booth, A., (2016) ‘Hell to pay: Religion and punitive ideology among the American public’ in Punishment and Society vol 18(2):151-176 Bartollas, C (2014) ‘Constituting the system: Radical developments in post-Newtonian society’ in Pycroft, A and Bartollas, C (eds) Applying Complexity Theory: Whole systems approaches to criminal justice and social work. Bristol. Policy Press: 269-286 Bash, A (2014) ‘Forgiveness, Reconciliation and Spirituality: a Theological Perspective’ in Journal for the Study of Spirituality 4(1): 58-72 Bash, A. (2015) Forgiveness: A Theology. Eugene, Oregon. Cascade Books Bergson, H. (1971) Time and Free Will. London. George Allen and Unwin Bergson, H. (1988) Matter and Memory. New York. Zone Books Bergson, H and Andison, M. (2010) The Creative Mind. Whitefish. Kessinger Publishing Breton, S. (2011). A Radical Philosophy of St Paul. New York. Columbia University Press Brewer, J., Mitchell, D. and Leavey, G. (2016) ‘ Northern Ireland: Religion and Transitional Justice’ Conflict Studies Quarterly 14: 74-91 Byrne, D. (1998) Complexity Theory and the Social Sciences: An Introduction. London. Routledge Byrne, D. and Callaghan, G. (2013). Complexity Theory and the Social Sciences: The state of the art. London. Routledge Cilliers, P. (1998) Complexity and Postmodernism: Understanding Complex Systems. London. Routledge Cilliers, P. (2005) ‘Complexity, Deconstruction and Relativism’ in Theory, Culture, Society Vol 22(5): 255-267 28 Cohen, S (2016) ‘Aristotle’s Metaphysics’ in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-metaphysics accessed 30/6/17 Colvin, C. (2000). 'We Are Still Struggling': Storytelling, Reparations and Reconciliation after the TRC. Research report written for the Centre for the Study of Violence and Reconciliation in collaboration with Khulumani (Western Cape) Victims Support Group and the Cape Town Trauma Centre for Survivors of Violence and Torture, December. Critchley, S. (2008) ‘What is continental philosophy’ in International Journal of Philosophical Studies 5(3): 347-365 Derrida, J. (2002). On Cosmopolitanism and Forgiveness. London: Routledge De Valve, M. (2017a) ‘O for a Muse of Fire: Rebellion as Sacrament’ in Critical Criminology 25: 87-102 De Valve, M. (2017b) ‘Love/Power’ in Critical Criminology 25: 375-391 Downie, D.S. (1965) ‘Forgiveness’ in Philosophical Quarterly Vol.15(59): 128-134 Dupuy, J.P. (2013) The Mark of the Sacred. Stanford. Stanford University Press Eddy, J. and Beilby, P (2006) ‘The atonement: An introduction’ in P. Beilby and J. Eddy (eds) The Nature of Atonement: Four Views. Illinois. IVP Academic: 9-21 Foucault, M. (1975). Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison. London. Virago Books Frazier, J. (1922) The Golden Bough: A Study in Magic and Religion. London. Macmillan and Co. Girard, R. (2007) Evolution and Conversion: Dialogues on the Origins of Culture. London. Continuum Books Girard, R. (2008) I See Satan Fall Like Lightening. Maryknoll. Orbis Books Girard, R. (1978) Things Hidden Since the Foundation of the World. London. Athlone Press Girard, R. (2014) The One by Whom Scandal Comes. East Lansing. Michigan University Press Gorringe, T. (1996) God’s Just Vengeance. Cambridge. Cambridge University Press Griswold, C (2007) Forgiveness: A Philosophical Exploration. Cambridge. Cambridge University Press Guastello, S. and Liebovitch, L. (2009)’Introduction to Nonlinear Dynamics and Complexity’ in S.Guastello.,M.Koopmans and D.Pincus (eds) Chaos and Complexity in Psychology: The Theory of Nonlinear Dynamical Systems. Cambridge. Cambridge University Press: 1-40 https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/aristotle-metaphysics%20accessed%2030/6/17 http://www.csvr.org.za/docs/trc/wearestillstruggling.pdf http://www.csvr.org.za/docs/trc/wearestillstruggling.pdf 29 Hathaway, O. (2003). ‘Path Dependence in the Law: the Course and Pattern of Legal Change in a Common Law System’ John M. Olin Centre for Studies in Law, Economics, and Public Policy Working Papers. Yale Law School Hawking, S. (1998). A Brief History of Time. Cambridge. Cambridge University Press Johnstone, G. and Van Ness,D.W (2007) ‘Roots of Restorative Justice’ in Johnstone, G. and Van Ness,D.W (eds) Handbook of Restorative Justice. Cullompton. Willan: 109-111 Kearney, R. and Rainwater, M. (1996). The Continental Philosophy Reader. London. Routledge Kearney, R. (1986) ‘Religion and Ideology: Paul Ricoeur’s Hermeneutic Conflict’ in The Irish Theological Quarterly 52: 109-126 Kearney, R. (1999). ‘Aliens and others: Between Girard and Derrida’ in Cultural Values Vol 3 (3): 251-262 Kearney, R. (2016) Re-imagining the Sacred. New York. Columbia University Press Kolnai, A. (1974) ‘Forgiveness’ in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 1973-4: 91-106 Lacey, N. and Pickard, H. (2015) ‘To blame or to forgive?: reconciling punishment and forgiveness in criminal justice’ Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, online pp. 1-31 DOI: 10.1093/ojls/ggv012 Levinas, E. (1969). Totality and Infinity: An essay on exteriority. Pittsburgh. Dequesne University Press Martin, D. (2014) Religion and Power: No Logos without Mythos. Farnham. Ashgate Massumi, B. (1996) A user’s guide to capitalism and schizophrenia: Deviations for Deleuze and Guattari. Cambridge. MIT Press Melamed, Y. (2012) ‘“Omnis determinatio est negatio” – Determination, Negation and Self- negation in Spinoza, Kant and Hegel’ in Forster, E. and Melamed, Y. (eds) Spinoza and German Idealism. Cambridge. Cambridge University Press: 175-196 Menocal, M.R. (2002). The Ornament of the World: How Muslims, Jews and Christians Created a Culture of Tolerance in Medieval Spain. New York. Bay Back Books Miller, J. (1990) ‘Carnivals of atrocity’ in Political Theory 18 (3): 470-491 Milanovanovic, D. (2014) Quantum Holographic Criminology: Paradigm Shift in Criminology, Law and Transformative Justice. Carolina Academic Press Murphy, J. and Hampton, J. (1988) Forgiveness and Mercy. Cambridge. Cambridge University Press 30 Nelson, M (1991) ‘Utilitarian Eschatology’ in American Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 28 (4): 339- 347 Nietzsche, F. (2008) The Birth of Tragedy. Oxford. Oxford University Press Nietzsche, F. (2003) Thus Spoke Zarathustra. London. Penguin Books Pellauer, D. and Dauenhauer, B. (2016) ‘Paul Ricoeur’ https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ricoeur/ accessed 8/12/17 Pepinksy, H. (2013) ‘Peacemaking Criminology’ in Critical Criminology 21:319-339 Pycroft, A. and Bartollas, C. (eds) (2014) Applying Complexity Theory: Whole systems approaches to criminal justice and social work. Bristol. Policy Press Pycroft, A (2014) ‘Complexity theory: an overview’ in Pycroft, A and Bartollas, C (eds) Applying Complexity Theory: Whole systems approaches to criminal justice and social work. Bristol. Policy Press: 15-38 Pycroft, A. (forthcoming) ‘Consciousness In Rather than Of: Advancing Modest Claims for the Development of Phenomenologically Informed Approaches to Complexity Theory in Criminology. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Criminology. Roberts, T. with Windle, J. (2015). Forgiven: The Amish School Shooting, a Mother's Love, and a Story of Remarkable Grace. Bloomington. Bethany House. Sieh, E. (1989) ‘Less Eligibility: The Upper Limits of Penal Policy’ in Criminal Justice Policy Review Vol.3: 159-183 Sydow, J., Schreyogg, G. and Koch, J. (2009). ‘Organizational Path Dependence: Opening the Black Box’ in Academy of Management Review Vol 34(4): 689-709 The Guardian http://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2015/nov/03/i-was-able-to- forgive-my-sisters-murderer-only-by-acknowledging-my-own-ange accessed 30/6/17 The Guardian http://www.theguardian.com/world/2015/apr/27/auschwitz-survivor-angers- plaintiffs-trial-forgiveness accessed 23/3/16 accessed 30/6/17 Verdeja, E. (2004) ‘Derrida and the Impossibility of Forgiveness’ in Contemporary Political Theory. Vol 3(1): 23-47 Žižek, S. (2011) Living in the End Times. London. Verso https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ricoeur/ http://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2015/nov/03/i-was-able-to-forgive-my-sisters-murderer-only-by-acknowledging-my-own-ange http://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2015/nov/03/i-was-able-to-forgive-my-sisters-murderer-only-by-acknowledging-my-own-ange http://www.theguardian.com/world/2015/apr/27/auschwitz-survivor-angers-plaintiffs-trial-forgiveness%20accessed%2023/3/16%20accessed%2030/6/17 http://www.theguardian.com/world/2015/apr/27/auschwitz-survivor-angers-plaintiffs-trial-forgiveness%20accessed%2023/3/16%20accessed%2030/6/17 work_lvombka7wvbcxenkntcwtfxevi ---- 0033.tif A Social Justice Agenda Vickie M. Mays University of California, Los Angeles T he m o r a l i m p e r a t i v e o f f e r e d to p s y c h o l o g y b y b o t h J a c k s o n (2000, this issue) and Strickland (2000, this i s s u e ) is to m o v e into this n e w c e n t u - r y l e a v i n g not one s i n g l e p e r s o n b e h i n d . N o one s h o u l d h a v e t h e i r future, t h e i r h e a l t h , or t h e i r w e l l - b e i n g c o m - p r o m i s e d f o r r e a s o n s o f c l a s s , g e n d e r , n a t i o n a l o r i g i n , p h y s i c a l a n d p s y c h o l o g i c a l a b i l i t i e s , r e l i g i o n , or s e x u - al o r i e n t a t i o n , or as a r e s u l t o f u n f a i r d i s t r i b u t i o n o f r e s o u r c e s . B o t h a u t h o r s e x h o r t p s y c h o l o g i s t s to w o r k d i l i g e n t l y to e n s u r e the b r i g h t e s t f u t u r e for all. In 1999, the A m e r i c a n Psychological Association (APA) embraced issues o f race, ethnicity, culture, and mul- ticulturalism. This focus was historic in its scope and re- sulted in rich contributions to the field. The presidency o f Richard Suinn, the first Asian American president o f APA, which coincided with the terms o f five division presidents drawn from persons o f color (D. W. Sue, Bingham, Porchr- Burke, & Vasquez, 1999), became an organizing force that concentrated the association's ability to address questions o f diversity, difference, and inequality (D. W. Sue et al., 1999). This was most evident at two meetings: the January 1999 National Multicultural Conference and Summit (NMCS) and A P A ' s 107th annual convention in August 1999. At the APA convention, m a n y psychologists participated in an opening ceremony o f cultural sharing, highlighted b y the interconnectedness o f the participants despite their m a n y differences. The Reverend Jesse Jackson spoke eloquently at the ceremony about the inequalities in U.S. society and the social problems they generate: increased violence, a sense o f hopelessness, deteriorating physical and mental health, and reductions in health care, social services, and the quality and amount o f educational resources. The tools o f psychology in the next century ought to address Strickland's and Jackson's concerns about those who are different. The tools should possess not only internal validity but extemal validity (S. Sue, 1999), or they will fail to address the inclusive social justice agenda that Jackson (2000), Strickland (2000), and the participants in the NMCS (D. W. Sue et al., 1999) see as A P A ' s moral imperative in t h i s next century. Psychology, as a discipline, needs also to ensure that its approaches to promoting psychological well- being and preventing mental disorders are culturally valid and available, delivered competently, and affordable to all who need them (Ziglio, Levin, & Bertinato, 1999). We can learn from the field o f public health, which advocates pre- vention at a community or population level to eliminate or significantly reduce morbidity (Albee, 1998a, 1998b). Ef- fective prevention will help individuals find ways o f build- ing their individual capacity, but achieving good mental health at an individual level is often beyond the control o f individuals. We enter the new millennium with the United States enjoying a sustained period o f extraordinary wealth. This wealth offers both unthought-of possibilities and dangers. On the one hand, we now possess the resources to address difficulties that can only be solved b y investment in our c o m m o n social future. On the other hand, g r o w i n g eco- n o m i c inequalities threaten our v e r y social c o h e s i o n (Ka- plan, 1996; Kaplan, P a m u k , L y n c h , Cohen, & Balfour, 1996; Wallace, 1996; Wilkinson, 1996; Wolff, 1995) and have presented the public with apparently senseless crimes where children kill children, where police kill the mentally ill, and where m a n y die from preventable illness because they were the last to get health care. At the same meeting where the Reverend Jackson spoke, Strickland (2000), in her Distinguished Contributions to Psychology in the Pub- lic Interest Award address, issued a summons for psycholo- gists to rise to the challenge issued at an APA meeting over 30 years ago by Dr. Martin Luther King, Jr., (1968) and renewed by Jackson (2000). I f p s y c h o l o g y is to show society the path to greater equality a m o n g its m e m b e r s , p s y c h o l o g i s t s m u s t d e m o n s t r a t e that p s y c h o l o g y ' s m e t h - ods and p r o c e d u r e s can e m b r a c e diversity. Whereas King worried primarily about gaps in equality between races, Jackson (2000) and Strickland (2000) p r e s e n t e d a b r o a d e r agenda in which they i m p l o r e d social scientists to under- stand that the behaviors they seek to study, modify, and eliminate are related to gaps resulting from poverty, inequal- ity, and inequity (Kawachi, Wilkinson, & Kennedy, 1999; Mays & Cochran, 1994, 1998; Mays, Coleman, & Jackson, 1996; Sampson, Raudenbush, & Earls, 1997). These behaviors are inextricably linked to wealth, economics, education, gov- ernmental policies, and even the professional policies of psychology. P s y c h o l o g y m u s t not focus i t s e l f solely on the m e n - tal health o f individuals w h e n the nation is trying to understand the senseless torture and death o f p e o p l e hated because o f their gender, race, religious beliefs, or sexual orientation. P s y c h o l o g i s t s must not l o o k m e r e l y to individual b e h a v i o r to grasp w h y a 12-year-old girl b e c o m e s pregnant intentionally, an l l - y e a r - o l d shoots another child, or police sodomize a man in custody, or to understand ethnic cleansings. Strickland (2000) observed that the future o f psychology requires psychologists to be willing to articulate, teach, and develop a body o f science informed b y social justice. Psychologists must not be afraid to teach, engage in clinical practice, and develop public policy Correspondence concerning this article should be addressed to Vickie M. Mays, University of California, 1283 Franz Hall, 405 Hilgard Avenue, Box 951563, Los Angeles, CA 90095-1563. Electronic mail may be sent to mays@ucla.edu. 326 March 2000 • American Psychologist Copyright 2000 by the American Psychological Association, Inc. 0003-066X/00/$5.00 Vol. 55, No. 3.32(~327 DOI: 10 1037//0003-066X.55.3.326 Vickie M. Mays a n d r e s e a r c h a b o u t r a c i s m , s e x i s m , c l a s s i s m , h o m o p h o b i a , a n d o t h e r d i v i s i v e p e r s p e c t i v e s t h a t e n a b l e p e o p l e t o t r e a t t h o s e w h o a r e d i f f e r e n t f r o m t h e m s e l v e s f a i r l y a n d c o m p e - t e n t l y . O u r p r o g r e s s as a d i s c i p l i n e , as a n a t i o n , a n d a s g l o b a l c i t i z e n s d e p e n d s o n o u r a b i l i t y t o i n c l u d e e v e r y o n e i n t h e f u t u r e - - t o b e f a i r t o all, n o t j u s t t o s o m e . REFERENCES Albee, G. W. (1998a). Fifty years of clinical psychology: Selling our soul to the devil. Applied and Preventive Psychology, 7, 189 194. Albee, G. W. (1998b). The politics of primary prevention. Journal o f Primary Prevention, 19, 117 127. Jackson, J. (2000). What ought psychology to do? American Psycholo- gist, 55, 328-330. Kaplan, G. A. (1996). People and places: Contrasting perspectives on the association between social class and health. International Journal o f Health Services, 26, 507-519. Kaplan, G. A., Pamuk, E. R., Lynch, J. W., Cohen, R. D., & Balfour, J. L. (1996). Inequality in income and mortality in the United States: Analysis of mortality and potential pathways. British Medical Jour- nal 312, 999-1003. Kawachi, I., Wilkinson, R. G., & Kennedy, B. (1999). Introduction. In I. Kawachi, B. P. Kennedy, & R. G. Wilkinson (Eds.), The society and population health reader: Income inequali~ and health (pp. xi- xxxiv). New York: New Press. King, M. L., Jr. (1968). The role of the behavioral scientist in the Civil Rights movement. American Psychologist, 23, 180-186. Mays, V. M., & Cochran, S. D. (1994). Depressive distress among homo- sexually active African American men and women. American Jour- nal o f Psychiat~, 151,524-529. Mays, V. M., & Cochran, S. D. (1998). Racial discrimination and health outcomes in African Americans [CD-ROM]. Proceedings o f the 27th Public Health Conference on Records and Statistics and the Nation- al Committee on Vital and Health Statistics 47th Annual Symposium. Washington, DC: U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. Mays, V. M., Coleman, L. M., & Jackson, J. S. (1996). Perceived race- based discrimination, employment status, and job stress in a national sample of Black women: Implications for health outcomes. Journal o f Occupational Health Psychology, 1, 319-329. Sampson, R. J., Raudenbush, S. W., & Earls, F. (1997, August 15). Neighborhoods and violent crime: A multilevel study of collective efficacy. Science, 277, 918-924. Strickland, B. R. (2000). Misassumptions, misadventures, and the mis- use of psychology. American Psychologist, 55, 331-338. Sue, D. W., Bingham, R. P., Porehr-Burke, L., & Vasquez, M. (1999). The diversification of psychology: A multieultural revolution. American Psychologist. 54, 1061-1069. Sue, S. (1999). Science, ethnicity, and bias: Where have we gone wrong? American Psychologist, 54, 1070-1077. Wallace, R. (1996). Inner-city decay and the health of the nation. Current Issues in Public Health, 2, 26-28. Wilkinson, R. G. (1996). Unhealthy societies: The afflictions o f ine- qualio'. London: Routledge. Wolff, E. N. (1995). Top hea~': A study' o f the increasing inequality o f wealth in America. New York: Twentieth Century Fund. Ziglio, 15., Levin, L. S., & Bertinato, L. (1999). Social and economic detemainants of health: Implications for promoting the health of the public. In D. Harrison & E. Ziglio (Eds.), Social determinants o f health: Implications .for the health professions (Forums in Experi- mental and Clinical Medicine, Suppl. 4). Retrieved February 17, 2000, from the World Wide Web: http://www.accmed.net/hpi/ documenti/index.htm M a r c h 2 0 0 0 • A m e r i c a n P s y c h o l o g i s t 3 2 7 work_lwcrlxtvnfhsfbtunnvwayamy4 ---- Blockchain technology – the ultimate solution for utmost cybersecurity LOGIN YourStory YourStory Club YourStoryTV HerStory SocialStory SMBStory More Companies Advertise With Us Makers-India AutoStory MyStory Weekender Journal YS Korea Deutschland Germany Events Visual English Kannada Hindi Tamil Asamiya Bangla Gujarati Malayalam Marathi Odia Punjabi Telugu Urdu அ अ ಅ Login English Kannada Hindi Tamil Asamiya Bangla Gujarati Malayalam Marathi Odia Punjabi Telugu Urdu அ अ ಅ Login Disclaimer: This is a user generated content for MyStory, a YourStory initiative to enable its community to contribute and have their voices heard. The views and writings here reflect that of the author and not of YourStory. Blockchain technology – the ultimate solution for utmost cybersecurity By Arpita Arya|2nd Feb 2018 Blockchain technology has created a sensation in the internet space. Let's get to learn more about the concept and terminologies.  0 claps +0 Share on 0 claps +0 Share on Share on What Is Blockchain Technology? Blockchain technology came into existence in 2008 and with the introduction of bitcoins, it became popular worldwide. According to Wikipedia, “blockchain is a continuously growing list of records, called blocks, which are linked and secured using cryptography”. This technology has created a sensation in the internet space which was originally invented by Satoshi Nakamoto.  Trading in cryptocurrencies does involve the high degree of risk. To solve these major concerns many tech communities like Blockchain-hero.com is spending sleepless nights to find other potential uses and solutions for the blockchain technology. The best part of this technology is that it eliminates the need for a third party to control the database which is shared among all the users. This distributed yet secured system initiated a new trend among the internet with lots of future scopes. Evolution Of Transaction Data Storage Data storage changed drastically after the invention of digital currencies also known as a cryptocurrency. In today’s date, there are more than 700 Bitcoin-like cryptocurrencies available in the market. They have finally set up the motion to be the principal form of transaction. This is mainly due to the growing online market in the current society. People shop online and carry out numerous operations on a daily basis. The emergence of cryptocurrency aimed at minimizing the exploitation of online customers from being overcharged by the middlemen.  The system, however, requires a series of record management technique that is decentralized. These are digital ledgers that are protected with cryptology encryption. The chain contains a series of blocks that secures and stores data relating to the transaction of each. The information is then stored permanently after being recorded and for later use and cannot be altered by a third party. The system is robust, transparent and incorruptible. Hence, the technology behind this system has gained so much attention worldwide. Why Implement Restricted Measures In Transactional Data Storage No person should be trusted with another person’s transactional data. Human beings will always act in self-interest. This has become the main motivating factor for blockchain sites advocating for implementation of blockchain system. The private key cryptography is the reason why bitcoin and cryptocurrencies were successful. Each user of the blockchain system has a secure transactional key that allows them to access their transactional data. Any other person can not manipulate the key. The key is also assigned to the user with a personal login signature. The signature is approved by all peers in the network for a transaction to take place. This system of encryption ensures data does not fall into fraudulent hands providing ultimate security. Trends In Blockchain technology Banks and Financial Institutions are trying to implement blockchain data storage technology into their systems to secure transactional data and track their financial activities at an optimum level. Financial institutions are already applying the system boost of unhackable systems. Various industries are also trying to create a reliable environment for their operations through creating unaltered systems that cannot be hacked or manipulated. Thus creating a perfect environment for forecasting and planning of their activities in the most secure manner. Get Inspired Innovation Business 0 Shares +0 Share on 0 Shares +0 Share on Share on Trending Now Trending Stories Google Doodle today celebrates the start of spring How Managed IT Services Benefit the Manufacturing Industry Arts and Social perception Ecommerce Mistakes That Make Your Users Abandon Your Website Daily Capsule Meesho turns unicorn, Swiggy raises mega round Read the full story Latest Updates from around the world Arts and Social perception How To Monitor Employees' Productivity? Art and environment Google Doodle today celebrates the start of spring A New CMO Role: Leveraging an Organization’s Purpose for Strategic Advantage How to accelerate Digital Business in 2021 Didn't find what you were looking for? Search for what you want, categories, tags, keywords, authors, events, anything under YourStory SEARCH Topics Tech Reviews Growth Hacks Government And Legal About Advertise with us About Meet the team Report an issue Contact Us Work with us Events © 2021 YourStory Media Pvt. Ltd. Privacy Policy v2.3.036 Built with ♥ in India work_m22wclsusbf53gzasoiegp44za ---- Experiences of youth justice: Youth justice discourses and their multiple effects McAlister, S., & Carr, N. (2014). Experiences of youth justice: Youth justice discourses and their multiple effects. Youth Justice: An International Journal, 14(3), 241-254. https://doi.org/10.1177/1473225414549694 Published in: Youth Justice: An International Journal Document Version: Peer reviewed version Queen's University Belfast - Research Portal: Link to publication record in Queen's University Belfast Research Portal Publisher rights © 2014 The Author General rights Copyright for the publications made accessible via the Queen's University Belfast Research Portal is retained by the author(s) and / or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing these publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Take down policy The Research Portal is Queen's institutional repository that provides access to Queen's research output. Every effort has been made to ensure that content in the Research Portal does not infringe any person's rights, or applicable UK laws. If you discover content in the Research Portal that you believe breaches copyright or violates any law, please contact openaccess@qub.ac.uk. Download date:06. Apr. 2021 https://doi.org/10.1177/1473225414549694 https://pure.qub.ac.uk/en/publications/experiences-of-youth-justice-youth-justice-discourses-and-their-multiple-effects(381addd8-1254-4d24-a43a-86ce276527ea).html 1 Experiences of youth justice: Youth justice discourses and their multiple effects Siobhán McAlister (School of Sociology, Social Policy and Social Work), Queen’s University Belfast, UK Nicola Carr (School of Sociology, Social Policy and Social Work), Queen’s University Belfast, UK Corresponding author: Siobhán McAlister, School of Sociology, Social Policy and Social Work, Queen’s University Belfast, Belfast, UK, BT71LP Email: s.mcalister@qub.ac.uk Abstract Interventions within youth justice systems draw on a range of rationales and philosophies. Traditionally demarcated by a welfare/justice binary, the complex array of contemporary rationales meld different philosophies and practices, suggesting a mutability that gives this sphere a continued (re)productive and felt effect. While it may be increasingly difficult to ascertain which of these discourses is dominant in different jurisdictions in the UK, particular models of justice are perceived to be more prominent (Muncie, 2006). Traditionally it is assumed that Northern Ireland prioritises restoration, Wales prioritises rights, England priorities risk and Scotland welfare (McVie, 2011; Muncie, 2008, 2011). However, how these discourses are enacted in practice, how multiple and competing rationales circulate within them and most fundamentally how they are experienced by young people is less clear. This paper, based on research with young people who have experienced the full range of interventions in the youth justice system in Northern Ireland examines their narratives of ‘justice’. It considers how different discourses might influence the same intervention and how the deployment of multiple rationalities gives the experience of ‘justice’ its effect. Key words Restorative justice, custody, youth justice discourse, experiencing justice 2 Introduction Across the UK the expansion of criminal and quasi-criminal interventions and modes of governance, alongside varied disposals and sanctions, has resulted in youth justice systems that enact multiple, contradictory and competing discourses (Fergusson, 2007; Muncie, 2004, 2006; Muncie and Goldson, 2006). While these are differentiated across time and place, the youth justice systems in separate jurisdictions within the UK tend to be associated with particular models of justice (e.g. welfare, rights, risk, restoration), and aspects of multiple discourses are evident in all. Research also demonstrates disjuncture between discourse, practice and experience whereby welfare-based models can be experienced coercively and punitively (McAra, 2006; Piacentini and Walters, 2006), and children’s rights can be used to justify intrusive interventions (Muncie, 2006). Further, the very nature of the discourses of welfare, rights, risk, responsibilisation, contain inherent tensions - care and control, child protection and public protection, child rights and victim rights. Thus, even where a particular model of youth justice is prominent, the meaning and experience is dependent on how interventions are institutionalised and enacted. Responses may be at the same time diversionary yet highly restrictive, welfare orientated yet punitive, rights focused yet exclusionary. Based on the narratives of young people who have encountered numerous criminal justice interventions, and set within the context of the Northern Irish system which prioritises restorative practices and a human rights policy discourse, this paper examines how the competing ideologies and aims of the system are experienced. Taking the forms of ‘justice’ most often administered to young people in an ongoing study, we consider their experiences of youth conferencing and custody. Youth Conferencing, based on the principles of restorative justice, encapsulates some of the multiple and competing discourses of youth justice - responsibilisation, punishment, reintegration, risk, (victim’s) rights. Custody is most often associated with the philosophical principles of punishment and public protection through incapacitation. Yet safeguards exist to limit its use with children and to protect those subjected to it. How these multiple and at times competing philosophies play out in the experiences of such interventions is examined. 3 Youth justice discourses Responses to young people in conflict with the law have usually taken account of their differential status to adults. Traditional justifications for intervention – welfare and justice – although less explicit today, continue to influence policy (Fergusson, 2007). As such, tensions and contradictions between care and control, welfare and justice exist alongside other articulations - rights and responsibilisation, punitiveness and informalisation - and are reflected to varying degrees (and sometimes simultaneously), in UK youth justice systems. Welfare-orientated policies and practices are premised on the special status of children, particularly regarding ‘responsibility’. Involvement in crime is linked with ‘social problems’, symbolic of deeper social and psychological difficulties rather than free rational and informed choice (Muncie, 2004). Interventions, therefore, prioritise the welfare needs of individual children which are better responded to outside the criminal justice system. Key is the aim to be child-centred, needs-focused and diversionary/ non-criminalising. These features appear to have much in common with more recent rights-based discourses of youth justice. Elements of this welfare model are also evident in current policies around diversion, prevention/ early intervention and multi-agency responses. However, welfare-based initiatives can also serve disciplinary and regulatory functions, resulting in net-widening and disproportionate interventions (Brown, 2005; Cohen, 1985; Muncie, 2004). Demonstrating the disjuncture between justice as discourse and justice as practiced and experienced, the welfare-orientated model can involve high levels of coercion and punitiveness with legal rights eroded and children silenced (Muncie, 2004; Piacentini and Walters, 2006). Welfare can, therefore, be about control as much as care, it can be punitive as well as protective. Concerns regarding lack of due process, proportionality and implementation of the rule of law, saw justice-based approaches foregrounded in recent years. With proponents arguing that a renewed focus on the offence (‘deeds’), rather than the ‘offender’ (‘needs’) would result in more proportionate responses (Muncie, 2004). 4 Young people in conflict with the law, while recognised as different to adults, are still rational actors, and thus responsible for their actions. Such rationalities marked the beginnings of what has been termed a ‘punitive turn’ in youth justice (Muncie, 2008) evidenced by ‘a general diminution of welfare-based modes of governance in favour of various “justice” based responsibilisation and managerial strategies’ (Muncie, 2005: 38). Taking the changes of the past few decades together (e.g. adulteration, penal expansionism, risk factor prevention and responsibilisation), Muncie (2008) argues that modes of youth governance are more punitive, repressive and expansive today. They are focused on punishment and individual responsibility rather than welfare, child protection and support. While rates of custody have traditionally be taken as an indication of a punitive and authoritarian approach, Cohen’s (1985) seminal work on the ‘dispersal of discipline’ is a reminder that a decline in imprisonment is not equated with less punishment and control. Further, in considering the fall in rates of youth custody in England and Wales, Bateman (2012) argues with reference to recent policy discourse, that this alone may not signal a shift in punitiveness. Risk, responsibilisation and rights: Multiple and contradictory discourses Contemporary youth justice involves multiple modes and layers of governance (Muncie, 2006). Recent initiatives focused on the prevention of offending through risk management illustrate the multiple and contradictory rationales within youth justice policy. Risk identification and management are premised on the basis of managing risk through intervening early in the lives of those displaying risk factors (Case, 2006). While early intervention programmes are presented as a benefit to the child and society, their welfare and rights-based ethos has been questioned (see Haydon this issue). In line with neo-liberal governance and the risk management agenda, a key element of contemporary youth justice is responsibilisation (Phoenix and Kelly 2013). Here the young offender is considered a ‘rational, responsible decision maker …’ (Gray, 2005: 938). The philosophical principles of restorative justice have married well with the responsibilisation agenda (Gray, 2005), because restorative justice emphasises 5 an acknowledgement by the young person of the harm done. The focus on restoration and reintegration, however, also reflects the welfare discourse. Thus restorative justice can embody some of the tensions between welfare and justice - holding young people to account but with a view towards them reintegrating into law- abiding society. Research into young people’s experiences of restorative justice has highlighted some of these tensions (Crawford and Newburn, 2003; Newbury, 2008). The range of interventions that often constitute restorative practices are individually focused, concentrating on the attitudes and behaviours of young people rather than the structural conditions of their lives (Gray, 2005). Newbury’s (2008) analysis challenges the reintegrative functions of restorative justice, noting that behaviour is unlikely to change if young people feel they must accept responsibility despite mitigating factors and broader explanations. Further demonstrating the tension between welfare and justice, restorative justice is embedded in the language of inclusion, participation and rights. Particularly suited to young people due to its ‘informal’ and sometimes diversionary nature, it incorporates the rights and views of victims and young people (e.g. Articles 12 and 40 of the UNCRC). Yet restorative justice can be experienced as punitive, exclusionary and shaming (Daly, 2002; Eliaerts and Dumortier, 2002). Concerns have also been raised regarding procedural safeguards in a forum where legal representation is absent (Eliaerts and Dumortier, 2002). While some research demonstrates relatively high levels of ‘engagement’ and participation by young people (e.g. Crawford and Newburn, 2003), this engagement and the levels of understanding of some has been questioned (Newbury, 2008). Whether young people feel they have a choice but to engage in the process, to accept responsibility and the resulting outcome is also debated (Hudson, 2003; O’Mahony and Campbell, 2006). In sum multiple, competing and contradictory discourses are reflected to different degrees in youth justice systems and interventions. While this is acknowledged, how these discourses play out and more fundamentally how they are experienced by young people is less clear. This paper, based on research with young people who have encountered a broad range of youth justice interventions examines their 6 experiences of ‘justice’. Through their narratives we consider how different discourses might influence the same intervention and how the deployment of multiple rationalities gives the experiences of ‘justice’ its effect. Youth justice in Northern Ireland: Prioritising restoration Elements of broader trends in youth justice including an increased focus on risk and the centrality of the victim are evident in Northern Ireland’s youth justice system (see Muncie, 2008, 2011; Muncie and Goldson, 2006). However, political conflict and subsequent conflict transformation have shaped the contours and structures of youth justice practice. This is most evident in the emergence of restorative justice as the main disposal. A core component of the peace process (1998) was a commitment to review policing and criminal justice and to embed accountability, human rights and transparency into institutions and their practices. Following from the Criminal Justice Review (2000), the Justice (NI) Act (2002) established a central agency with responsibility for youth justice and set out the aims of the new youth justice system. Here the principle aim is the protection of the public through preventing offending by children. Emphasising the centrality of responsibilisation, young people are to be encouraged ‘to recognise the effects of crime and to take responsibility for their actions’. These aims are to be implemented with consideration for the welfare of the child. The ordering of these principles, in particular the relegation of welfare has been the subject of some critique (Youth Justice Review Team, 2011). Further, these aims demonstrate the multiple discourses underpinning the system. The discourses of risk, responsibilisation and public protection sit alongside those of welfare, rehabilitation and rights. The Justice (Northern Ireland) Act (2002) introduced new diversionary disposals, community and custodial orders and formalised restorative justice through the Youth Conference Service. Adapting methods of conflict resolution restorative justice is reflective of the wider aims of transitional justice intended to close the legitimacy gap in state administered criminal justice (Doak and O’Mahony, 2011). The legislation provides that where a young person admits guilt the Public Prosecution Service 7 (PPS) or the Court must direct that a Youth Justice Conference is held unless the offence falls under a small number of excluded serious offencesi. The output of the youth conference, the Conference Plan, is approved by either of the directing parties (PPS or Court). Conference Plans typically contain requirements for the young person to write a letter of apology to a victim, and to engage in forms of reparative work and other purposeful activities. Over time the numbers of youth conferences has risen markedly. A total of 1,556 referrals for a conference were made to the Youth Justice Agency in 2012-2013 compared to 172 referrals in 2005 (DeCodts and O’Neill, 2014). As youth conferencing has expanded and become the primary youth justice response, the numbers of young people in custody has declined. The transformation of Northern Ireland’s youth justice system and in particular the emphasis on restoration has been hailed internationally as a success story (Doak and O’Mahony, 2011; Jacobson and Gibbs, 2009). However, this transformation is not uncontested (Convery, 2013; Convery et al., 2008). In respect of restorative justice, the efficacy and proportionality of multiple conferencing has been questioned (CJINI, 2008; Youth Justice Review Team, 2011). Criticisms similar to those previously described have emerged in local research. Specifically: problems with the focus on individual responsibility; feelings of a lack of inclusion and ‘equal’ input from young people; oppressive and punitive proceedings and disproportionate outcomes (see Maruna et al., 2007; O’Mahony and Campbell, 2006). Overall, however, the experiential aspects of youth justice have been given less coverage in broader narratives about system transformation. A decline in the use of custody and the prominence of restoration do not necessarily account for how justice is perceived in practice – whether for example restoration is found to be responsibilising or reintegrative. Given the multiplicity of rationales and the range of young people to whom they are applied inevitably there will be differing accounts of these experiences. In the next section we explore how such rationales are played out for young people. Methodology and background to the study 8 The data presented in this article is based on interviews with young people who were remanded or serving a sentence in Woodlands Juvenile Justice Centre (JJC). Woodlands is a purpose-built facility managed and staffed by the Youth Justice Agency (YJA). The centre accommodates almost all young people under 18 detained within the criminal justice systemii. Young people can also be detained here under Police and Criminal Evidence (PACE) provisions, following arrest and charge and pending their court appearance. The ongoing study, funded by the YJA, focuses on the transitions of young people into and out of custody. Research participants were selected on a purposive basis taking account of the heterogeneity of the population including gender, routes of admission, offences and home areaiii. The sample includes 21 young people, two young women and 19 young men, aged between 15 and 17 at the time of the first interview. The first interview normally takes place in the JJC prior to the young person’s release. It comprises of a life-history interview (Atkinson, 1998; Coles and Knowles, 2001), where young people are invited to ‘tell the story of their life’ including the reasons why they are detained at this time. In addition to exploring the young person’s previous contacts with the criminal justice system, the interview explores their hopes and plans for the future, particularly the plans in place for their release from custody. Follow-up interviews take place following young people’s release from custody; here the focus is on their transition from custody, what has been happening in their lives and any challenges that have arisen. The data presented in this article focuses specifically on young people’s experiences of justice. Here we focus on two aspects of the youth justice system – restorative justice (youth conferencing) and custody. Young people’s experiences of justice Most of the young people had multiple interactions with the youth justice system over a sustained period of time. A number had contact with the criminal justice system prior to reaching the age of criminal responsibility (age 10) through family involvement and contacts with the police. Experiences with the police were often fraught. There were numerous accounts of feeling over-policed (particularly in discussing the policing of bail conditions), and expressions of discrimination and targeting. In addition to formal policing, around half of the sample (n=11) had also 9 experienced ‘policing’ by paramilitaries. This included intimidation, threats and warnings, physical beatings and exilings. This informal punishment, regulation and control when added to experiences with the formal criminal justice system, amounted to multiple forms of punishment. While for a small number of young people contact with the criminal justice system was minimal, more usual was a long history of involvement with young people having experienced a number of previous interventions, including remands into custody, extensive bail conditions, youth justice conferences and community-based sanctions. Under legislation there is no limit to the number of youth conferences that a young person can be made subject to and many of the young people that we interviewed had taken part in multiple conferences. Restorative justice Based on restorative justice principles, the purpose of the youth conference as outlined in guidance for young people is toiv: … give you a chance to tell the people at the meeting why you committed the offence. It gives the victim a chance to tell you how they have been affected by what you did to him or her. …The meeting will want you to: …. Agree an action plan to make up for what you have done and stop offending. Young people reported variable experiences of this process. For some, conferencing, or at least what they were required to do for their conference plan, provided some structure in their lives. Kyle, who was on remand for a serious violent offence and who had multiple previous offences, explained how the activities required under his conference plans provided him with something to fill his time: I: …did you ever find the conferences useful or helpful? R: No, it just got me off the streets really. So they gave me something stable so they did, ‘cos I was going in and out of there (YJA) 4 or 5 days a week like so I was. And if I hadn’t been doing it, I would have been just lying awake getting stoned like. Kyle (age 16) 10 It is noteworthy that it was not the content of the programmes that Kyle identified as useful, or the conference itself, rather that the Plan provided him with purposeful activity. At the time of his initial interview, Kevin was serving his first custodial sentence for involvement in riotous behaviour. He had previous convictions for similar offences and had been through the youth conference process. His account of some of the requirements of his conference plan provides an example of having to confront the impacts of his offending. On this occasion Kevin describes visiting a residence to hear about the impact of rioting on those living there: …because I was rioting outside an ‘aul (old) people’s home, I went up…and I writ them a letter saying I was sorry, and then I went up telling them I was all sorry. And then they took me on a wee tour around the place…I felt alright saying sorry, but I felt like an asshole for rioting outside their place, so I did...It made me feel a bit lousy on them and all because of how close it was…I went and met the manager, ‘cos they were saying – ‘how do you feel’?, and all And I said – ‘I feel like a …dickhead’ and all that there. And I went around and said sorry and I was shaking people’s hands saying I was sorry for rioting outside and I writ them a letter… This experience had a clear impact on Kevin. As he described it, meeting the residents of the home made him feel a sense of shame. The shaming element of restorative justice draws on the theory of ‘reintegrative shaming’ (Braithwaite, 1989), which contends that social disapproval impacts on how a person feels about their offence, ideally dissuading them from such behaviour in the future. A component of this approach, and an underlying premise of restorative justice, is that a reintegration or restoration takes place for the victim of the offence and for the offender (Harris, 2006). Thus, a distinction is drawn between reintegrative shaming – i.e. shaming that is respectful of the person, avoids labelling and ends with forgiveness – and stigmatizing shaming (Ahmed and Braithwaite, 2005). 11 While Kevin spoke about the salutary effect of this particular conference, he had subsequently been convicted of further rioting offences resulting in his current sentence. Sometimes explaining his behaviour in individual terns (defining himself as a ‘hood’v), Kevin also described his feelings of boredom, the lack of things to do in his community and by contrast the excitement of rioting: ‘you get like an adrenaline rush so you do…it’s good.’ Within the local context rioting has historically been a masculine form of cultural expression and resistance (Haydon et al, 2012). It can be seen, therefore, that despite restorative interventions the context and circumstances of Kevin’s life, continued to impact heavily on his offending behaviour. For some young people, their experiences of conferences were more stigmatizing than reintegrative. Aged 15, and serving a sentence for a violent offence Paul had experience of multiple conferences. He recounted his first conference where the victim was antagonistic towards him: I had to show remorse for what I’d done like…like for the different offences, like I was in a youth conference there ages ago for a burglary, it was one of my first offences, and I just got diverted to a youth conference because it wasn’t a serious burglary, you know. I had to sit in a room with the person from the shop and I had to sit there and just to listen to him and say sorry and all. He just sat there and gave me abuse basically, he was an English boy and he called me a ‘yob’ or something like that. I hadn’t a clue what that meant, I had to say – ‘what the fuck’s a yob like?’ And he says a ‘hood’ or something like that it is. And I said – ‘I’m no hood’. Over time and following participation in further conferences, Paul describes ‘wising up’ and learning what is expected of him: You know, that was me back in that time, and then going through youth justice and all, I started wising up a bit, started getting street smart you know instead of being stupid. Just all I had to do, all of the youth conferences, then after that I would have just sat there and said ‘sorry’. You know, just listening to them go on and on, (I) wouldn’t give a fuck. I would have sat there and said ‘sorry’ instead of arguing with them, you know what I mean? Paul (age 15) 12 Clearly Paul had learnt to adapt his initial strategy of resistance, challenging and talking back, to one where he says the ‘sorry’ that is required of him. The inclusive and participatory nature of conferences was greatly questionable in Paul’s experience. Garrett (age 17) described a similar feeling of saying what is required: …you just have to sit down, and basically pretend, or not pretend, say you’re sorry and look like you’re sorry and that’s it… Part of the difficulty here arises from the over-simplified binary categorisations of ‘victim’ and ‘offender’, and for some the sense of injustice this arouses. Taking the moment, the interaction of the offence as the instance in which the young person (the ‘offender’) is held to account, and in which s/he must demonstrate remorse and accountability before the legitimate ‘victim’, belies the realities of many of the young people’s lives beyond these moments. For, Hugh (age 16), his life had been characterised by multiple losses and he described intense feelings of despair. Youth conferences where he had to account for behaviour that he could not fully recall because of alcohol use were particularly difficult: …just like sitting there and listening, listening to like listening to everything that I did and ‘cos it was all alcohol and it was all I felt so shit about it like, so bad. And see like a few months down the line at that conference listening to it again like just… you know when the alcohol was on board I didn’t care and then a few months down the line I had the conference just hearing it all again it was just killer like. Strategies of responsibilisation ‘holding young people to account’ are evident from the official youth justice discourse and in young people’s own recounting of their experiences. Internalising the message of the need to take responsibility and self- manage Hugh feels the responsibility to change, particularly in light of a further admission to custody, as resting firmly on his shoulders. Despite recognising the harm done and feeling deep shame, Huge recognised this was not enough: 13 I’d say if you asked … the conference worker well I wouldn’t really say it hit home much with where I am sitting (in custody) at the moment. It’s up to me to change it like. While Morris (2002) cautions against a false binary between restorative and retributive justice or indeed pinning unrealistic expectations on restorative processes, here the challenges of restoration are apparent. While the focus of any conference is on the harm caused, the meaningfulness of restoration and reintegration particularly into families and communities from which young people feel alienated is raised in many of the young people’s accounts. Recognising the harms caused by offending was not something young people typically shied away from, however, they recounted the responsibility for restoration as resting primarily on them. The contents of Conference Plans, perhaps reflecting the offending history of some, were at times expansive and onerous. Some noted the ‘stress’ that managing multiple conditions could cause and a few noted not agreeing with the outcomes even though they had accepted them. While few discussed the programmes they had to undertake in any manner that would suggest a rehabilitative effect, their value for providing something to do in otherwise monotonous lives is noteworthy in its own right. It speaks to the lack of opportunities for young people living in communities often beleaguered by poverty, under-investment and the legacies of the Conflict. Experiences of custody Paradoxically, but perhaps unsurprisingly given their life experiences and ongoing issues within their communities, for many young people detention was described as a period of respite. Having their needs met and the relative ‘ease’ of the JJC in comparison to life outside was evident: Life is so easy in here. You have no worries about people looking for you, no worries about nothing. You have no worries about going hungry and getting food and things like that. Robbie (aged 16) Reference was made to the range of activities available in the Centre and the fact that there was a structure and routine to daily life: 14 It’s a gift. I don’t know, don’t worry about nothing like. Whatever you need is there…the food’s rotten though. There’s all sorts of activities you can do in it like. They show you options and everything you can do when you get out and all. Patrick (age 17) Anthony (aged 17) had been in and out of the JJC since the age of 11. He estimated that he had spent two years in detention between various remands and sentences. Using drugs for many years – ‘solvies and meth and coke, E’s everythin’ - for him the JJC offered an opportunity to detox: I like it in here, it’s good…Cos it’s kinda a detox centre, you just come in and get off all the drugs and all and get fit again. Anthony (age 17) Raising questions about the availability of appropriate services for young people in the community, like Anthony, Hugh had also experienced multiple admissions and the JJC was a place where he came off drugs. While ultimately he saw this as positive, this process was not without its pains: It makes me feel, it’s like I try, and this place is sort of like a place where people come off things. This is hard, you have to come off things in here … it is not like you can turn round and say ‘give me something, give me cannabis, give me a smoke’. You can’t, you have to do it you have to come off them. And it is hard like… I have got these shakes sometimes I feel real not meself and but that’s why I do alternatives like go to the gym, do weights just take me mind of things really. Better than sitting smoking me brains out you know. Hugh (age 16) The experience of many young people was that the JJC met their welfare needs, underlining the fact that these were not being met elsewhere. In a number of interviews young people also noted the materiality of their surroundings in detention. Some who had come here for the first time reported that it did not meet their expectations of what a prison or place of detention would be - they had their own rooms and access to resources that were not necessarily available to them on the 15 outside. This is not to suggest that young people did not want their freedom, and that there were not pains associated with confinement, but in many accounts the positive welfarist aspects of having their basic needs met, whilst at the same time desiring to be on the outside were noted. For some, like Hugh the desire to be free in the literal sense and also from drugs was double-edged, because he was not sure if he would have somewhere to go on release or if he could sustain abstinence on the outside. The anticipation of rejection by his family who did not want him to return home permeated his account and while he desired to be free, the thought of what would happen to him on release was a source of anxiety: I don’t have a problem with bein’ in here (custody) ‘cos, I don’t know, I guess you just get used to it after a few times. But then it’s just the fact that when you have bail you just have nowhere to live, it’s the worst thing that could possibly happen to ya. Hugh (age 16) Contact with families and friends on the outside was both a source of comfort and anxiety for many young people. Some young people worried about their families making the journey to visit them, they described looking forward to a visit but feeling down afterwards as this accentuated their experience of being confined and away from home. Because the JJC is the only place for detained young people in Northern Ireland many families have to make long journeys to get there. While the JJC has an accommodation unit where families and visitors can stay overnight, young people were often conscious about the burden that their detention placed on their families. For Stevie, the impact of his mother visiting was known as he witnessed it first hand when his older brother was in prison: … when (brother was in prison) me ma went up and down but she used to be stressed, she says ‘this is costing me a fortune’. Diesel and then needin’ fifty pound a time for buyin’ clothes and all that. I knew it was a nightmare like, that’s why I said ‘I’ll see you once I get out’, but she came up the last time and left me money and all… 16 For young people then, experiences of custody were both punitive in terms of the deprivation of liberty and all that entailed, but also welfarist in that they perceived their needs were being met where they were not elsewhere. Discussion and conclusion Young people’s accounts of their experiences of these two justice interventions - youth conferencing and custody - provide an illustration of the range of rationalities at play within the youth justice system. The mix of responsibilisation, restoration, welfarism and punitiveness is evident. The impulse towards responsibilisation of ‘holding young people to account’ for the harms they have caused is clear in some of the experiences of restorative justice, where young people are required to hear the views of the victims of their offences and to make amends. Depending on the particular circumstances and dynamics of the process, these encounters can be experienced as shameful or punitive. They can also become devoid of meaning, a performance of reform where young people understand the rules and what is required of them - they ‘wise up’ and they give the requisite apology. In other instances experiences of shaming are characterised more re-integratively. A clear pre-requisite here is that the young person feels that they are treated with respect and that they are not stigmatised within this process. The aim of restoration as young people experience it, largely places the burden of restoration and reform on their shoulders. The question of their wider experiences, including multiple traumatic life events, poverty, paramilitary punishments and other forms of exclusions are for many not addressed in a meaningful way. This is not to say that attempts are not made to do this, young people are provided with the opportunity to give their account, but for many this accounting in this setting is too difficult and to what effect? While the formulations of conference plans variously include letters of apology, engagement in voluntary work, attendance at anger management and drug and alcohol programmes and so forth, these too are largely premised on indivualised reform and responsibility. That incarnations of restorative justice do not achieve the desired effects for these and other young people is not a reason to rubbish its intentions (Morris, 2002). The 17 point is to illuminate the fact that discourses are given multiple effects in practice. Here restoration as perceived is about responsibiisation and for some it is punitive. Similarly the data on young people’s experiences of custody, an intervention most associated with punitiveness, points to contradictory strains and ‘oscillating rationales’ (Muncie, 2006: 771) in the youth justice sphere. The accounts of young people highlight that for some detention was the means to meet their welfare needs and this was preferable to them than circumstances where their freedom in the community was restrictively curtailed, for example through the imposition of multiple bail conditions. Thus, a contingent community existence was viewed more punitively than custody. The argument is not of course that custody should not espouse welfarist rationales, but rather that this was the place where welfare needs (substance misuse and mental health difficulties, homelessness, etc.) had to be met. This is the larger indictment. While the numbers of young people in custody over time has declined, the impulse for its use, grounded in such rationales – preventative, public protection and welfarist - remains. It is the multiplicity and adaptability of these various rationales that continue to give custody and other youth justice interventions their (re)productive and felt effect. References Ahmed E and Braithwaite J (2005) Forgiveness, shaming, shame and bullying. Australian and New Zealand Journal of Criminology 38(3): 298–323. Atkinson R (1998) The Life Story Interview. London: Sage. Bateman T (2012) Who pulled the plug? Towards an explanation for the fall in child imprisonment in England and Wales. Youth Justice 12(1): 36-52. Braithwaite J (1989) Crime, shame and reintegration. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. 18 Brown S (2005) Understanding Youth and Crime: Listening to Youth? Berkshire: Open University Press. Case S (2006) Young People “At Risk” of What? Challenging Risk-focused Early Intervention as Crime Prevention. Youth Justice 6(3): 171-179 Cohen S (1985) Visions of Social Control. Cambridge: Polity Press. Cole AL and Knowles GJ (2001) Lives in context: The Art of Life History Research. Lanham: AltaMira Press. Convery U, Haydon D, Moore L and Scraton P (2008) Children, Rights and Justice in Northern Ireland: Community and Custody. Youth Justice 8(3): 245-263. Convery U (2013) Locked in the past: An historical analysis of the legal framework of custody for children in Northern Ireland. European Journal of Criminology 11(2): 251- 269. Crawford A and Newburn T (2003) Recent Developments in Restorative Justice for Young People in England and Wales: Community Participation and Representation. British Journal of Criminology 42(3): 476-495. Daly K (2002) Restorative Justice the real story. Punishment and Society 4(1): 55- 79. DeCodts M and O’Neill N (2014) Youth Justice Agency Annual Workload Statistics 2012/13 Statistical Bulletin 1/2014. Belfast: DoJ (Department of Justice). Doak J and O’Mahony D (2012) In search of legitimacy: restorative youth conferencing in Northern Ireland. Legal Studies 31(2): 305-325. Eliaerts C and Dumortier E (2002) ‘Restorative justice for children: in need of procedural safeguards and standards.’ In: Weitekamp EGM and Kerner HJ (eds.) Restorative Justice Theoretical Foundations. Cullompton: Willan, pp. 204-223. 19 Fergusson R (2007) Making sense of the melting pot: Multiple discourses in Youth Justice Policy. Youth Justice 7(3): 179-194. Gray P (2005) The politics of risk and young offenders’ experiences of social exclusion and restorative justice. British Journal of Criminology 45(6): 938-957. Haydon, D., McAlister, S., Scraton, P. (2012) ‘Young People, Conflict and Regulation.’ Howard Journal of Criminal Justice, 51,5: 503-520 Harris N (2006) Reintegrative Shaming, Shame, and Criminal Justice. Journal of Social Issues 62(2): 327-346. Hudson B (2003) Understanding Justice: An Introduction to Ideas, Perspectives and Controversies in Modern Penal Theory. Buckingham: Open University Press. Jacobson J and Gibbs P (2009) Making Amends: Restorative Justice in Northern Ireland. London: Prison Reform Trust. McAra L (2006) Welfare in crisis? Key developments in Scottish Youth Justice. In: Muncie J and Goldson B (eds.) Comparative Youth Justice. London: Sage, pp. 127- 145. McVie S (2011) Alterative models of youth justice: lessons from Scotland and Northern Ireland. Journal of Children’s Services 6(2): 106-114. Maruna S, Wright S, Brown J, Van Marle F, Devlin R and Liddle M (2007) Youth Conferencing as Shame Management: Results of a Long-Term Follow-up Study. ARCS UK: Available at: http://youthjusticeagencyni.gov.uk/document_uploads/SHAD_MARUNA_STUDY.pdf Morris A (2002) Critiquing the critics: A brief response to critics of restorative justice. British Journal of Criminology 42(3): 596-615 20 Muncie J (2004) Youth and Crime, London: Sage. Muncie J (2005) The globalization of crime control – the case of youth and juvenile justice: Neo-liberalism, policy convergences and international conventions. Theoretical Criminology 9(1): 35-64. Muncie J (2006) Governing young people: Coherence and contradiction in contemporary youth justice. Critical Social Policy 26(4): 770–793. Muncie J (2008) The ‘punitive turn’ in juvenile justice: Cultures of control and rights compliance in Western Europe and the USA. Youth Justice 8(2): 107-121. Muncie J (2011) Illusions of difference: Comparative youth justice in the devolved United Kingdom. British Journal of Criminology 51(1): 40-27. Muncie J and Goldson B (2006) States of transition: Convergence and diversity in international youth justice. In: Muncie J and Goldson B (eds.) Comparative Youth Justice. London: Sage, pp. 196-218. Newbury A (2008) Youth crime: Whose responsibility? Journal of Law and Society 35(1): 131-149. O’Mahony D and Campbell C (2006) Mainstreaming Restorative Justice for Young Offenders through Youth Conferencing: The Experience of Northern Ireland. In: Junger-Tas J and Decker SH (eds.) International Handbook of Juvenile Justice, pp. 93-115. Phoenix J and Kelly L (2013) “You have to do it yourself”: Responsibilzation in youth justice and young people’s situated knowledge of youth justice practice. British Journal of Criminology 53(3): 419-437. Youth Justice Review Team (2011) A Review of the Youth Justice System in Northern Ireland. Belfast: DoJ 21 Author biographies: Siobhán McAlister and Nicola Carr are lecturers in Criminology in Queen’s University Belfast i The following offences are precluded from being dealt with by way of a youth justice conference under the Justice Act, 2002 [33A, 2](a) offences the sentence for which is, in the case of an adult, fixed by law as imprisonment for life; (b) offences which are, in the case of an adult, triable only on indictment; and(c) offences which are scheduled offences for the purposes of Part 7 of the Terrorism Act 2000 (c. 11). ii In line with recommendations for The Youth Justice Review (2011), in late 2012 the Department of Justice announced the end of detention of under 18’s within the prison system, except in specific cases (e.g. where there were serious security risks such as the involvement of a young person in dissident activity). iii Young people who are currently looked after are not included in the sample as this requires a separate research governance and ethical approval process. iv Youth Justice Agency leaflet for young people: Youth Conference: Your Decision. Available at: http://www.youthjusticeagencyni.gov.uk/document_uploads//Youth_conference_Your_Decision.pdf v ‘Hood’ is a localism for those who take part in criminal activities, particularly rioting with the police, for ‘fun’. http://www.youthjusticeagencyni.gov.uk/document_uploads/Youth_conference_Your_Decision.pdf work_m42vtsuxazdvhlqkynn7qbpbb4 ---- 164 Crime and Justice serious crimes such as serious assault, sexual assault, robbery or housebreaking. The Sexual Offences Act 2003 introduced in May 2004 altered the definition and coverage of sexual offences. In particular, it redefined indecent exposure as a sexual offence, which is likely to account for much of the increase in sexual offences. Further information is available from Crime in England and Wales 2007/2008 (Home Office, Sian Nicholas, Chris Kershaw and Alison Walker, editors). Court proceedings and police cautions (Tables 11.4 to 11.8, 11.13 to 11.17, 11.20 to 11.22) The statistical basis of the tables of court proceedings is broadly similar in England and Wales, Scotland and Northern Ireland; the tables show the number of persons found guilty, recording a person under the heading of the principal offence of which they were found guilty, excluding additional findings of guilt at the same proceedings. A person found guilty at a number of separate court proceedings is included more than once. The statistics on offenders cautioned in England and Wales cover only those who, on admission of guilt, were given a formal caution by, or on the instructions of, a senior police officer as an alternative to prosecution. Written warnings by the police for motor offences and persons paying fixed penalties for certain motoring offences are excluded. Formal cautions are not issued in Scotland. There are no statistics on cautioning available for Northern Ireland. The Crime and Disorder Act 1998 created provisions in relation to reprimands and final warnings, new offences and orders which have been implemented nationally since 1 June 2000. They replace the system of cautioning for offenders aged under 18. Reprimands can be given to first-time offenders for minor offences. Any further offending results in either a final warning or a charge. For persons proceeded against in Scotland, the statistics relate to the High Court of Justiciary, the sheriff courts and the district courts. The High Court deals with serious solemn (that is, Jury) cases and has unlimited sentencing power. Sheriff courts are limited to imprisonment of 3 years for solemn cases, or 3 months (6 months when specified in legislation for second or subsequent offences and 12 months for certain statutory offences) for summary (that is, non-Jury) cases. District courts deal only with summary cases and are limited to 60 days imprisonment and level 4 fines. Stipendiary magistrates sit in Glasgow District Court and have the summary sentencing powers of a sheriff. Crime and Justice There are differences in the legal and judicial systems of England and Wales, Scotland and Northern Ireland which make it impossible to provide tables covering the UK as a whole in this section. These differences concern the classification of offences, the meaning of certain terms used in the statistics, the effects of the several Criminal Justice Acts and recording practices. Recorded crime statistics (Table 11.3) Crimes recorded by the police provide a measure of the amount of crime committed. The statistics are based on counting rules, revised with effect from 1 April 1998, which are standard for all the police forces in England, Wales and Northern Ireland and now include all indictable and triable- either-way offences together with a few summary offences which are closely linked to these offences. The new rules have changed the emphasis of measurement more towards one crime per victim, and have also increased the coverage of offences. These changes have particularly impacted on the offence groups of violence against the person, fraud and forgery, drugs offences and other offences. For a variety of reasons many offences are either not reported to the police or not recorded by them. The changes in the number of offences recorded do not necessarily provide an accurate reflection of changes in the amount of crime committed. In order to further improve the consistency of recorded crime statistics and to take a more victim oriented approach to crime recording, the National Crime Recording Standard (NCRS) was introduced across all forces in England, Wales and Northern Ireland from 1 April 2002. Some police forces implemented the principles of NCRS in advance of its introduction across all forces. The NCRS had the effect of increasing the number of offences recorded by the police. Similarly, the Scottish Crime Recording Standard (SCRS) was introduced by the eight Scottish police forces with effect from 1 April 2004. This means that no corroborative evidence is required initially to record a crime-related incident as a crime if so perceived by the victim. Again, the introduction of this new recording standard was expected to increase the numbers of minor crimes recorded by the police, such as minor crimes of vandalism and minor thefts and offences of petty assault and breach of the peace. However, it was expected that the SCRS would not have much impact on the figures for the more 165 Crime and Justice In England and Wales, indictable offences are offences which are: • triable only on indictment. These offences are the most serious breaches of the criminal law and must be tried at the Crown Court. ‘Indictable-only’ offences include murder, manslaughter, rape and robbery • triable either way. These offences may be tried at the Crown Court or a magistrates’ court The Criminal Justice Act 1991 led to the following main changes in the sentences available to the courts in England and Wales: • introduction of combination orders • introduction of the ‘unit fine scheme’ at magistrates’ courts • abolishing the sentence of detention in a young offender institution for 14-year-old boys and changing the minimum and maximum sentence lengths for 15 to 17- year-olds to 10 and 12 months respectively, and • abolishing partly suspended sentences of imprisonment and restricting the use of a fully suspended sentence The Criminal Justice Act 1993 abolished the ‘unit fine scheme’ in magistrates’ courts, which had been introduced under the Criminal Justice Act 1991. A charging standard for assault was introduced in England and Wales on 31 August 1994 with the aim of promoting consistency between the police and prosecution on the appropriate level of charge to be brought. The Criminal Justice and Public Order Act 1994 created several new offences in England and Wales, mainly in the area of public order, but also including male rape (there is no statutory offence of male rape in Scotland, although such a crime may be charged as serious assault). The Act also: • extended the provisions of section 53 of the Children and Young Persons Act 1993 for 10 to 13-year-olds • increased the maximum sentence length for 15 to 17-year- olds to 2 years • increased the upper limit from £2,000 to £5,000 for offences of criminal damage proceeded against as if triable only summarily • introduced provisions for the reduction of sentences for early guilty pleas, and • increased the maximum sentence length for certain firearm offences Provisions within the Crime (Sentences) Act 1997 (as amended by the Powers of Criminal Courts Sentencing Act 2000) in England and Wales, and the Crime and Punishment (Scotland) Act 1997 in Scotland, included: • an automatic life sentence for a second serious violent or sexual offence unless there are exceptional circumstances (this provision has not been enacted in Scotland) • a minimum sentence of 7 years for an offender convicted for a third time of a class A drug trafficking offence unless the court considers this to be unjust in all the circumstances, and • in England and Wales, the new section 38A of the Magistrates’ Courts’ Act 1980 extending the circumstances in which a magistrates’ court may commit a person convicted of an offence triable-either-way to the Crown Court for sentence – it was implemented in conjunction with section 49 of the Criminal Procedure and Investigations Act 1996, which involves the magistrates’ courts in asking defendants to indicate a plea before the mode of trial decision is taken and compels the court to sentence or commit for sentence any defendant who indicates a guilty plea Under the Criminal Justice and Court Service Act 2000 new terms were introduced for certain orders. Community rehabilitation order is the new name for a probation order. A community service order is now known as a community punishment order. Finally, the new term for a combination order is community punishment and rehabilitation order. In April 2000 the secure training order was replaced by the detention and training order. Section 53 of the Children and Young Persons Act 1993 was repealed on 25 August 2000 and its provisions were transferred to sections 90 to 92 of the Powers of Criminal Courts (Sentencing) Act 2000. Reparation and action plan orders were implemented nationally from 1 June 2000. The drug treatment and testing order was introduced in England, Scotland and Wales from October 2000. The referral order was introduced in England, Scotland and Wales from April 2000. These changes are now reflected in Table 11.8. The system of magistrates’ courts and Crown Courts in Northern Ireland operates in a similar way to that in England and Wales. A particularly significant statutory development, however, has been the Criminal Justice (NI) Order 1996 which introduces a new sentencing regime into Northern Ireland, largely replicating that which was introduced into England and Wales by the Criminal Justice Acts of 1991 and 1993. The order makes many changes to both community and custodial sentences, while introducing new orders such as the combination order, the custody probation order, and orders for release on licence of sexual offenders. 166 Crime and Justice Expenditure on penal establishments in Scotland (Table 11.19) The results shown in this table are reported on a cash basis for financial years 1996/97 to 2000/01 in line with funding arrangements. Financial year 2001/02 is reported on a resource accounting basis in line with the introduction of resource budgeting. Capital charges were introduced with resource accounting and budgeting. 167 Crime and justice 11.1 Police force strength 1: by countr y and sex As at 31 March Numbers 1998 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 2008 England and Wales Regular Police(FTE) Strength: Men KERB 105 145 103 956 101 801 102 321 104 483 106 996 110 150 110 597 109 327 108 118 106 866 Women KERC 19 611 19 885 20 155 21 155 22 784 24 430 26 956 28 898 30 307 31 914 32 861 Seconded:2,3 Men KERD 1 836 2 017 2 077 1 914 2 031 1 689 1 811 1 514 1 545 422 432 Women KERE 222 238 307 292 305 251 284 222 203 60 70 Additional Officers:4 Men KERF 267 324 361 493 567 375 394 522 676 657 661 Women KERG 514 582 519 509 564 709 969 1 042 1 213 1 203 1 471 Special constables Strength:5 Men KERH 11 977 10 860 9 623 8 630 8 014 7 718 7 645 8 074 8 829 9 327 9 719 Women KERI 6 279 5 624 4 724 4 108 3 584 3 319 3 343 3 844 4 350 4 694 4 828 Scotland Regular police Strength:6 Men KERK 12 753 12 545 12 374 12 547 12 513 12 590 12 685 12 798 12 820 12 687 12 532 Women KERL 2 227 2 265 2 325 2 602 2 738 2 897 2 898 3 203 3 401 3 547 3 689 Central service:7 Men KERM 85 88 95 87 116 131 166 195 171 153 219 Women KERN 6 9 13 10 12 17 29 29 21 28 44 Seconded:8 Men KERO 101 85 130 140 133 166 192 216 200 195 196 Women KERP 10 12 18 14 18 24 30 31 27 28 30 Additional regular police: Men HFVM 88 85 80 83 80 79 88 79 85 107 106 Women HFVN 9 6 4 5 12 10 13 21 15 12 14 Special constables Strength: Men KERS 1 286 1 229 981 924 812 711 773 718 888 886 884 Women KERT 437 422 355 336 307 280 328 437 432 471 510 Nor thern Ireland Regular police9,10 Strength: Men KERU 7 523 7 406 6 844 6 227 6 057 6 171 6 108 6 016 5 992 5 949 5 761 Women KERV 933 987 966 1 009 1 080 1 266 1 418 1 547 1 534 1 600 1 653 Reser ve11 Strength: Men KERW 3 469 3 199 2 962 2 629 2 223 1 983 1 824 1 431 1 424 1 212 1 119 Women KERX 705 641 607 556 510 453 485 410 402 400 382 1 Figures for England and Wales excluding those on career breaks or mater nity/pater nity leave . From 1999, figures for Norther n Ireland reflect the position at the end of the financial year, prior to this figures were as at 31 December. 2 Figures exclude secondments outside the police service in England and Wales (eg to the private sector or to law enforcement agencies overseas). 3 From 31 March 2007 onwards details of officers seconded to NCIS and NCS will no longer appear following the launch of Serious Organised Crime Agency (SOCA) in April 2006. 4 Figures include those officers on career breaks or maternity/pater nity leave . Pr ior to 2003, these figures were not collected centrally. 5 Special constable figures are given as a headcount measure. 6 ’Strength’ is FTE police strength, only excluding special constables. 7 Instr uctors at Training Establishments, etc, for merly shown as second- ments. 8 Includes Scottish Crime and Drug Enforcement Agency. 9 Does not include officers on secondment. 10 Also includes student officers. 11 Includes par t-time reser ve and full-time reserve , FTR -664 as at 31 March 2008 (618 males and 46 females). Con PT - 837 as at 31 March 2008 (501 males and 336 females). Sources: Home Office: 020 7035 0289; Scottish Government Justice Department: 0131 244 4253; The Police Service of Norther n Ireland: 028 9065 0222 ext 24070 168 Crime and justice 11.2 Prison Population1 international comparisons Rate16 per 100,000 % change population in Countr y 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 2006-2007 2007 England & Wales5 67 056 71 324 72 992 75 057 76 896 79 085 80 692 2 149 Nor thern Ireland3 910 1 026 1 160 1 274 1 301 1 433 1 468 2 83 Scotland7 6 137 6 404 6 524 6 805 6 792 7 111 7 291 3 142 Austr ia 6 915 7 511 7 816 9 000 8 767 8 780 8 887 1 107 Belgium12 8 544 8 605 9 308 9 245 9 375 9 635 10 008 4 94 Bulgar ia3 8 971 8 994 9 422 10 066 10 871 11 436 11 058 -3 144 Croatia3 2 623 2 584 2 732 2 803 3 022 3 485 3 833 10 86 Cypr us 369 345 355 546 536 599 673 12 85 Czech Republic6 19 320 16 213 17 277 18 343 18 937 18 578 18 901 2 182 Denmar k 3 150 3 439 3 577 3 762 4 132 3 759 3 406 -9 62 Estonia3 4 803 4 775 4 352 4 576 4 565 4 411 4 327 -2 322 Finland6 3 110 3 469 3 463 3 535 3 883 3 477 3 370 -3 64 Fr ance10 47 005 53 463 57 440 56 271 56 595 55 754 60 677 9 95 Ger many4 80 333 74 904 81 176 81 166 80 410 78 581 75 719 -4 92 Greece9 8 343 8 284 8 555 8 760 9 589 10 113 10 700 6 96 Hungar y6 17 275 17 838 16 507 16 543 15 720 14 821 14 353 -3 143 Iceland 110 107 112 115 119 119 115 -3 37 Ireland (Eire)13 3 025 3 028 2 986 3 083 3 022 3 080 3 325 8 76 Italy6 57 203 56 723 56 845 56 068 59 523 39 005 48 693 25 82 Latvia3 8 831 8 531 8 366 8 179 7 646 6 965 6 548 -6 287 Lithuania3 9 516 11 566 11 070 8 063 8 125 8 137 8 079 -1 239 Luxembourg 357 380 498 548 693 756 745 -1 155 Malta11 257 283 278 277 298 346 387 12 95 Nether lands 15 246 16 239 18 242 20 075 21 826 20 463 18 103 -12 110 Norway 2 666 2 662 2 914 2 975 3 097 3 164 3 280 4 69 Poland5 80 004 80 610 80 692 79 344 82 656 87 669 90 199 3 237 Portugal6 13 260 13 918 13 835 13 152 12 889 12 636 11 587 -8 109 Romania6 49 840 48 081 42 815 39 031 36 700 34 038 29 390 -14 137 Russian Federation3 925 072 980 151 877 393 847 004 763 115 823 451 871 693 6 613 Slovakia6 7 433 7 758 8 873 9 422 8 897 8 249 7 986 -3 148 Slovenia 1 155 1 120 1 099 1 126 1 132 1 301 1 336 3 66 Spain 46 962 50 994 55 244 59 224 61 269 64 120 66 400 4 148 Sweden15 6 089 6 506 6 755 7 332 7 054 7 175 6 770 -6 74 Switzer land14 5 137 4 937 5 214 5 977 6 137 5 888 5 715 -3 76 Turkey 61 336 60 091 64 051 71 148 54 296 67 795 85 865 27 122 Ukraine 198 885 198 946 198 386 193 489 179 519 165 716 154 055 -7 332 Australia2 22 458 22 492 23 555 24 171 25 353 25 790 27 224 6 130 Canada8 35 533 35 736 35 868 34 155 34 365 35 110 - - 108 Japan3 61 242 65 508 69 502 73 734 76 413 79 052 81 255 3 63 Korea(Rep. of)7 62 235 61 084 58 945 57 184 52 403 46 721 46 313 -1 96 Mexico6 165 687 172 888 182 530 193 889 205 821 210 140 212 841 1 193 New Zealand7 5 887 5 738 6 059 6 556 7 100 7 595 7 959 5 188 South Africa4 170 959 178 998 189 748 187 640 187 394 150 302 161 639 8 339 U.S.A.2 1 961 247 2 033 331 2 081 580 2 129 802 2 186 230 2 245 189 2 299 116 2 762 European Union 27 581 419 592 331 607 522 609 873 620 099 601 513 611 078 2 123 1 At 1 September : number of prisoners, including pre-trial detainees/remand pr isoners. 2 At 30 June. 3 At 1 Januar y. 4 At 31 March. 5 At 31 August. 6 At 31 December. 7 Annual averages. Countr ies calculate these on the basis of daily, weekly or monthly figures. 8 Annual averages by financial year (e.g. 2006=1 April 2005-31 March 2006). Rate per 100,000 population reflects the position in 2006. 9 At 1 September (2001-03, 2005-06). At 16 December (2004). At 30 June (2007). 10 Metropolitan and overseas departments and territor ies. 11 At 1 September (2001-06). Annual average (2007). 12 At 1 March. 13 At 1 September (2001-06). At 26 October (2007). 14 At third Wednesday in March (2001). At first Wednesday in September (2002-07). 15 At 1 October. 16 Based on estimates of national population. Sources: Ministries responsible for prisons, national prison administrations; national statistical offices, Council of Europe Annual Penal Statistics (SPACE); World Prison Population List and Wor ld Pr ison Br ief; (Inter national Centre for Prison Studies King’s College, London) 169 Crime and justice 11.3 Recorded crime statistics: by offence group 1 England and Wales Thousands 1997 19982,3 19983 1999 2000 20014 20024,6 2003 2004 2005 20068 2007 /99 /00 /01 /02 /03 /04 /05 /06 /07 /08 Violence against the person BEAB 250.8 434.3 LQMP 502.8 581.0 600.9 650.3 845.1 967.2 1 048.1 1 059.6 1 046.4 961.2 Sexual offences7 BEAC 33.2 35.9 LQMQ 36.2 37.8 37.3 41.4 58.9 62.5 62.9 62.1 57.5 53.5 Burglar y BEAD 1 015.0 966.3 LQMR 953.2 906.5 836.0 878.5 890.1 820.0 680.4 645.1 622.0 583.7 Robber y BEAE 63.1 63.8 LQMS 66.8 84.3 95.2 121.4 110.3 103.7 91.0 98.2 101.4 84.7 Theft and handling stolen goods (of which): BEAF 2 164.9 2 172.4 LQMT 2 191.4 2 223.6 2 145.4 2 267.0 − − − − − − Offences against vehicles I8RM .. .. .. .. 1 074.7 985.0 820.1 792.8 765.0 656.5 Other theft offences I8RN .. .. .. .. 1 336.9 1 327.9 1 247.6 1 226.2 1 180.8 1 121.1 Fr aud and forger y BEAG 134.3 236.7 LQMU 279.5 334.8 319.3 314.9 331.1 319.6 280.1 232.8 199.7 155.4 Cr iminal damage BEAH 877.0 866.5 LQMV 879.6 945.7 960.1 1 064.5 1 120.6 1 218.5 1 197.5 1 184.3 1 185.0 1 036.2 Dr ug offences5 LQMO .. 21.3 LQYT 135.9 121.9 113.5 121.4 143.3 143.5 145.8 178.5 194.2 229.0 Other offences5 BEAI 36.6 57.3 LQYU 63.6 65.7 63.2 65.7 64.0 65.7 64.0 75.6 75.7 69.3 Total BEAA 4 598.3 4 943.7 LQYV 5 109.1 5 301.2 5 170.8 5 525.0 5 975.0 6 013.8 5 637.5 5 555.2 5 427.6 4 950.7 1 See chapter text. 2 Estimates. 3 Figures from this period are not directly comparable with data prior to 1998/99 and from 2002/03 onwards. 4 The National Crime Recording Standard (NCRS) was introduced in Eng- land and Wales from 1 April 2002. These figures are not directly compara- ble with those for earlier years. For more details about the inflationary ef- fects of the NCRS on the 2001/02 and 2002/03 figures see chapter text. A detailed explanation for the NCRS can be accessed via the following Home Office Research Development and Statistics website http://www.homeof- fice.gov.uk/rds/countr ules.html 5 Prior to 1 April 1998 the offence of drug trafficking was included in the ’Other offences’ group. From 1 April 1999, under the new counting rules, drug traffick- ing became part of a new ’Dr ug offences’ group which, now also includes pos- session and other drug offences. For 1998/99 under the old counting rules, dr ug trafficking has been separated out and listed under drugs offences. 6 Includes the British Transpor t Police (BTP) from 2002/03 onwards. 7 The Sexual Offences Act 2003, introduced in May 2004, altered the definitions and coverage of sexual offences. 8 The offence groupings were revised in 2006/07 and backdated to 2002/03. Source: Home Office: 020 7035 0307 170 Crime and justice 11.4 Offenders found guilty: by offence group 1,2,3, England and Wales Magistrates’ courts and the Crown Court Thousands 1997 1998 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 All ages4 Indictable offences Violence against the person: KJEJ 34.6 35.7 34.4 34.0 35.3 37.7 38.0 39.1 40.9 41.9 42.1 Murder KESB 0.3 0.3 0.3 0.3 0.3 0.3 0.3 0.4 0.4 0.4 0.4 Manslaughter KESC 0.3 0.3 0.3 0.3 0.3 0.3 0.2 0.3 0.3 0.2 0.2 Wounding KESD 32.7 35.2 33.9 33.5 33.5 35.7 35.9 36.9 38.6 39.8 40.0 Other offences of violence against the person KESE 1.3 1.3 1.3 1.3 1.2 1.4 1.5 1.3 1.3 1.2 1.5 Sexual offences KESF 4.5 4.6 4.3 3.9 3.8 4.4 4.4 4.8 4.8 4.9 5.1 Burglar y KESG 31.7 30.8 29.3 26.2 24.8 26.7 25.7 24.3 23.0 23.0 23.8 Robber y KESH 5.6 5.5 5.6 6.0 6.8 7.7 7.3 7.5 7.1 8.1 8.8 Theft and handling stolen goods KESI 118.4 125.7 131.2 128.0 127.0 127.3 119.1 110.6 103.8 99.0 106.0 Fr aud and forger y KESJ 17.0 19.8 20.3 19.2 18.3 18.1 18.0 18.1 18.5 18.2 19.9 Cr iminal damage KESK 10.5 10.9 10.9 10.2 10.7 11.0 11.2 11.7 11.7 12.7 12.5 Dr ugs KBWX 40.7 48.8 48.7 44.6 45.6 49.0 51.2 54.5 39.1 39.6 44.6 Other offences (excluding motor ing) KESL 47.6 49.6 47.9 44.5 44.2 48.0 51.4 54.7 53.1 50.0 45.3 Motor ing offences KESM 9.5 9.0 8.1 7.6 7.7 8.2 8.7 8.0 6.6 5.9 5.4 Total KESA 320.1 341.7 342.0 325.5 324.2 338.3 335.1 317.8 308.5 303.2 313.3 Summar y offences Assaults KESO 32.0 35.3 37.5 37.4 37.7 40.7 45.6 53.4 60.4 64.5 68.9 Betting and gaming KESP − − − − − − − − − − − Offences with pedal cycles KBWY 1.5 2.1 1.3 0.8 0.6 0.5 0.6 0.7 0.7 0.7 0.7 Other Highways Acts offences KBWZ 3.2 3.1 2.9 2.7 2.4 2.2 1.9 1.8 2.0 2.1 1.7 Breach of local or other regulations KESQ 6.4 5.8 6.5 5.0 4.3 3.9 3.4 3.1 2.6 1.9 1.6 Intoxicating Liquor Laws: Dr unkenness KESR 28.8 30.8 28.7 27.2 26.2 26.9 27.7 21.1 16.1 15.7 17.4 Other offences KESS 0.6 0.6 0.5 0.4 0.3 0.4 0.7 0.8 1.0 1.2 1.0 Education Acts KEST 3.7 5.0 5.1 5.1 5.6 5.8 5.8 6.5 6.4 7.4 8.4 Game Laws KESU 0.3 0.4 0.3 0.2 0.2 0.3 0.2 0.2 0.4 − 0.1 Labour Laws KESV 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.1 − − − − − − − Summar y offences of criminal damage and malicious damage KESW 24.7 26.5 27.9 28.0 26.9 28.3 29.8 31.5 31.1 30.2 32.1 Offences by prostitutes KESX 6.6 6.0 4.0 4.1 3.7 4.2 3.9 2.9 2.2 1.6 1.4 Railway offences KESY 11.4 12.6 15.2 17.4 22.6 29.4 34.8 35.0 40.2 44.6 46.0 Revenue Laws KESZ 143.5 174.7 165.8 175.0 146.9 167.8 172.5 175.5 130.5 104.4 104.8 Vagrancy Acts KETB 2.0 2.2 2.7 3.3 3.2 3.8 3.8 2.9 2.2 2.2 2.0 Wireless Telegraphy Acts KETC 77.0 76.6 55.8 105.7 83.8 96.6 79.9 89.3 105.0 115.6 121.0 Other summary offences KETD 74.7 80.9 79.3 78.1 77.8 76.4 82.9 97.9 108.2 103.6 86.0 Motor ing offences (summary) KETA 649.3 665.2 632.9 607.5 583.3 595.8 662.6 707.9 667.1 622.5 611.1 Total KESN 1 065.8 1 128.0 1 066.5 1 098.2 1 025.5 1 083.0 1 156.1 1 230.7 1 175.9 1 118.2 1 102.6 Persons aged 10 to under 185 Indictable offences Violence against the person: KETF 5.9 5.9 6.2 6.4 6.9 6.9 6.6 6.9 7.4 7.5 7.7 Murder KBXA − − − − − − − − − − − Manslaughter KBXB − − 0.2 − − − − − − − − Wounding KBXC 5.8 5.9 5.9 6.3 6.8 6.8 6.5 6.5 7.3 7.4 7.6 Other offences of violence against the person KCAA 0.1 0.1 − 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.3 0.2 0.1 0.1 Sexual offences KETG 0.5 0.5 0.5 0.5 0.5 0.6 0.4 0.6 0.6 0.5 0.5 Burglar y KETH 8.6 8.5 7.8 6.8 6.3 6.4 5.8 5.9 6.0 6.2 6.1 Robber y KETI 2.3 2.2 2.0 2.2 2.8 2.8 2.6 3.0 3.1 3.7 4.1 Theft and handling stolen goods KETJ 19.6 21.9 22.7 21.0 20.6 18.4 16.5 16.8 17.1 16.3 18.2 Fr aud and forger y KETK 0.8 1.0 1.1 1.0 1.0 1.2 0.8 0.8 0.7 0.6 0.7 Cr iminal damage KETL 2.3 2.3 2.7 2.6 2.9 2.9 2.9 3.2 3.3 3.7 3.6 Dr ugs KCAB 1.8 2.7 3.1 3.7 4.3 5.0 5.1 4.5 4.6 4.5 5.3 Other offences (excluding motor ing) KETM 4.2 4.2 4.3 4.4 4.4 4.4 4.3 4.6 4.5 4.1 4.2 Motor ing KETN 0.4 0.4 0.4 0.6 0.7 0.8 0.8 0.7 0.6 0.5 0.4 Total KETE 46.4 49.7 50.6 49.2 50.3 49.1 46.0 47.0 47.8 47.6 50.9 Summar y offences Offences with pedal cycles KETP 0.2 0.3 0.3 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.3 0.2 0.2 Breach of local or other regulations KETR 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.1 Summar y offences of criminal damage and malicious damage KETS 4.4 5.2 6.1 6.7 6.9 7.0 7.2 8.3 8.8 8.6 9.2 Railway offences KETT 0.5 0.5 0.5 0.4 0.4 0.4 0.3 0.4 0.4 0.4 0.5 Other summary offences KETU 16.6 19.4 20.0 20.2 20.8 20.6 20.9 23.1 24.0 24.7 26.8 Motor ing offences (summary) KCAC 10.8 11.3 12.6 14.5 16.7 17.1 17.8 17.0 14.8 12.1 9.9 Total KETO 22.0 36.8 39.6 42.2 45.2 45.4 46.6 49.2 48.3 46.1 46.6 1 See chapter text. 2 Data provided on the principal offence basis. 3 Every effor t is made to ensure that the figures presented are accurate and complete. How ever, it is impor tant to note that these data have been ex- tracted from large administrative data systems generated by the courts and police forces. As a consequence, care should be taken to ensure data col- lection processes and their inevitable limitations are taken into account when those data are used. 4 Includes ’Companies’, etc . 5 Figures for persons aged 10 to under 18 are included in the totals above . Sources: Office for Criminal Justice Refor m: 020 7035 4955; Evidence and Analysis 171 Crime and justice 11.5 Offenders cautioned: by offence group 1,2,3 England and Wales Thousands 1997 1998 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 All ages4 Indictable offences Violence against the person KELB 23.6 23.5 21.2 19.9 19.5 23.6 28.8 36.6 51.0 57.3 52.3 Murder KCAD − − − − − − − − − − − Manslaughter KCAE − − − − − − − − − − − Wounding KCAF 23.3 22.9 20.6 19.3 18.9 22.9 27.9 35.0 49.6 55.7 50.8 Other violence against the person KCAG 0.4 0.6 0.6 0.6 0.6 0.7 0.9 1.2 1.4 1.5 1.6 Sexual offences KELC 1.9 1.7 1.5 1.3 1.2 1.1 1.4 1.6 1.8 1.9 2.0 Burglar y KELD 9.4 8.4 7.7 6.6 6.4 5.8 5.6 5.6 6.5 7.7 7.0 Robber y KELE 0.7 0.6 0.6 0.6 0.5 0.4 0.4 0.5 0.6 0.7 0.6 Theft and handling stolen goods KELF 82.8 83.6 75.4 67.6 63.5 54.2 54.5 61.9 67.6 72.4 72.8 Fr aud and forger y KELG 7.2 7.4 7.2 6.2 5.8 5.3 5.5 6.0 6.9 8.0 8.6 Cr iminal damage KELH 2.8 2.7 3.0 3.2 3.4 3.1 3.7 5.5 7.2 9.0 8.8 Dr ug offences KCAI 56.0 58.7 49.4 41.1 39.4 44.9 45.7 32.6 34.4 37.4 43.0 Other offences KELI 5.0 5.0 4.6 4.4 4.1 4.4 5.3 6.0 6.9 9.3 10.0 All offenders cautioned KELA 189.4 191.7 170.6 150.9 143.9 142.9 150.7 156.3 182.9 203.7 205.1 Summar y offences Assaults KELK 9.1 .. 17.0 17.2 18.2 17.3 19.8 26.1 40.8 64.6 72.6 Betting and gaming KELL − − − − − − − − − − − Offences with pedal cycles KCAK 0.9 0.8 0.6 0.3 0.2 0.1 0.1 0.3 0.3 0.3 0.3 Other Highways Acts offences KCAL 0.8 0.8 0.7 0.4 0.3 0.2 0.3 0.3 0.2 0.3 0.3 Breach of local or other regulations KELM 0.9 0.9 0.7 0.5 0.3 0.3 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.1 0.1 Intoxicating Liquor Laws: Dr unkenness KELN 25.7 22.8 20.3 18.1 16.6 16.2 18.1 13.5 8.6 5.8 6.1 Other offences KELO 0.9 0.7 0.4 0.2 0.3 0.3 0.3 0.3 0.3 0.2 0.2 Education Acts KELP − − − − − − 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.1 Game Laws KELQ 0.1 0.1 0.1 − − − − − − − − Labour Laws KELR − − − − − − − − − − − Summar y offences of criminal damage and malicious damage KELS 27.6 28.3 28.7 26.8 26.7 24.7 27.6 33.3 38.0 43.2 44.3 Offences by prostitutes KELT 3.5 3.5 2.1 1.3 1.0 1.8 1.3 1.6 1.4 1.2 1.2 Railway offences KELU 0.1 − − − − − − − 0.1 0.1 0.1 Revenue Laws KELV 0.1 0.1 0.1 − − − − − − − − Vagrancy Acts KELX 0.6 1.2 0.8 0.4 0.3 0.3 0.3 0.2 0.3 0.4 0.5 Wireless Telegraphy Acts KELY − − − − − − − − − − − Other summary offences KELZ 22.3 37.0 24.1 22.5 21.9 21.0 22.9 23.5 25.2 29.2 32.1 All offenders cautioned KELJ 92.7 96.2 95.6 88.1 85.9 82.4 91.1 99.5 115.5 145.6 157.8 Persons aged 10 to under 185 Indictable offences Violence against the person KEMB 9.6 9.5 8.5 8.3 8.7 9.3 11.0 13.6 16.5 16.6 13.9 Murder KCAN − − − − − − − − − − − Manslaughter KCAO − − − − − − − − − − − Wounding KCAP 9.6 9.4 8.4 8.2 8.6 9.2 10.9 13.5 16.4 16.5 13.8 Other violence against the person KCCE − 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.1 Sexual offences KEMC 0.7 0.6 0.6 0.5 0.5 0.4 0.5 0.5 0.6 0.6 0.7 Burglar y KEMD 7.5 6.7 6.1 5.4 5.3 4.6 4.4 4.2 4.6 5.0 4.5 Robber y KEME 0.6 0.5 0.5 0.5 0.5 0.4 0.4 0.4 0.5 0.6 0.5 Theft and handling stolen goods KEMF 40.9 44.0 39.6 36.9 35.2 28.1 28.3 33.1 36.8 39.4 39.7 Fr aud and forger y KEMG 1.4 1.6 1.7 1.5 1.3 1.1 1.0 1.0 1.1 1.3 1.4 Cr iminal damage KEMH 1.8 1.7 1.9 2.1 2.3 1.9 2.3 3.1 3.9 4.7 4.5 Dr ug offences KCCF 9.7 11.0 9.6 7.9 8.5 9.5 9.6 8.3 7.8 7.1 8.0 Other offences KEMI 1.5 1.5 1.4 1.3 1.3 1.3 1.4 1.6 1.6 1.9 2.0 All offenders cautioned KEMA 73.7 77.2 69.8 64.3 63.5 56.6 58.7 65.9 73.4 77.1 75.2 Summar y offences Offences with pedal cycles KEMK 0.5 0.4 0.3 0.2 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 Breach of local or other regulations KEMM 0.3 0.3 0.2 0.2 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.1 Summar y offences of criminal damage and malicious damage KEMN 13.5 14.2 14.7 14.4 15.2 12.6 14.3 17.1 19.8 21.9 21.7 Railway offences KEMO 0.1 − − − − − − − − − − Other summary offences KEMP 16.4 17.7 19.0 18.4 19.1 17.1 18.8 21.7 25.1 29.6 30.2 All offenders cautioned KEMJ 30.8 32.5 34.2 33.2 34.5 29.9 33.3 39.1 45.1 51.7 52.1 1 See chapter text. 2 Data provided on the principal offence basis. 3 Every effor t is made to ensure that the figures presented are accurate and complete. How ever, it is impor tant to note that these data have been ex- tracted from large administrative data systems generated by police forces. As a consequence, care should be taken to ensure data collection pro- cesses and their inevitable limitations are taken into account when those data are used. 4 Includes ’Companies’, etc. 5 Figures for persons aged 10 to under 18 are included in the totals above . Sources: Office for Criminal Justice Refor m: 020 7035 4955; Evidence and Analysis 172 Crime and justice 11.6 Offenders found guilty of offences: by age and sex 1,2,3 England and Wales Magistrates’ courts and the Crown Court Thousands 1997 1998 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 Males Indictable offences All ages KEFA 276.5 292.9 291.7 276.5 275.5 287.1 283.4 268.4 261.3 258.4 267.0 10 and under 15 years KEFB 7.1 8.1 8.9 8.7 9.0 8.8 8.0 8.5 8.6 8.3 8.5 15 and under 18 years KEFC 33.6 35.2 35.1 33.8 34.4 33.7 31.4 31.8 32.0 32.5 35.0 18 and under 21 years KEFD 48.4 51.8 52.6 49.9 48.2 46.6 43.8 39.9 38.5 39.0 40.6 21 years and over KEFE 187.3 197.9 195.0 184.0 183.9 198.0 200.2 188.2 182.2 178.7 182.9 Summar y offences All ages KEFF 880.9 929.0 886.6 881.0 826.6 866.4 937.1 990.0 931.2 877.7 851.5 10 and under 15 years KEFG 3.0 3.9 5.1 5.8 6.2 6.1 6.1 6.7 7.2 7.0 7.5 15 and under 18 years KEFH 25.9 28.5 30.3 32.2 34.5 34.6 35.3 36.4 34.6 32.3 31.9 18 and under 21 years KEFI 91.0 96.3 94.8 93.0 92.2 94.7 99.9 98.2 89.4 85.1 80.5 21 years and over KEFJ 761.0 800.3 756.5 750.0 693.6 731.0 795.8 848.8 800.1 753.4 731.8 Females Indictable offences All ages KEFK 42.2 47.3 49.0 47.7 47.4 50.0 50.2 48.4 46.1 43.7 45.3 10 and under 15 years KEFL 1.0 1.4 1.4 1.5 1.6 1.6 1.6 1.7 1.7 1.7 1.7 15 and under 18 years KEFM 4.6 5.1 5.2 5.2 5.3 5.1 4.9 5.0 5.5 5.1 5.5 18 and under 21 years KEFN 6.3 7.1 7.6 7.5 7.0 6.9 6.2 5.7 5.3 4.8 4.6 21 years and over KEFO 30.4 33.7 34.7 33.5 33.5 36.5 37.5 35.9 33.6 32.1 33.4 Summar y offences All ages KEFP 174.9 188.3 171.0 208.3 190.2 208.7 210.5 231.2 236.6 233.9 244.2 10 and under 15 years KEFQ 0.5 0.6 0.8 0.9 0.9 1.1 1.2 1.4 1.6 1.6 1.7 15 and under 18 years KEFR 3.4 3.8 3.4 3.3 3.6 3.6 4.0 4.6 4.9 5.2 5.6 18 and under 21 years KEFS 11.1 12.1 10.8 11.8 11.1 11.6 12.6 13.0 13.5 14.2 14.9 21 years and over KEFT 160.0 171.7 155.4 192.3 174.7 192.4 192.7 212.1 216.6 212.9 221.9 Companies, etc Indictable offences KEFU 1.3 1.5 1.3 1.3 1.3 1.2 1.4 1.1 1.1 1.0 1.1 Summar y offences KEFV 10.0 10.7 8.9 8.8 8.6 7.9 8.6 9.4 8.1 6.6 6.9 1 See chapter text. 2 These data are on the principal offence basis. 3 Every effor t is made to ensure that the figures presented are accurate and complete. How ever, it is impor tant to note that these data have been ex- tracted from large administrative data systems generated by the courts and police forces. As a consequence, care should be taken to ensure data collection processes and their inevitable limitations are taken into account when those data are used. Source: Office for Criminal Justice Refor m: 020 7035 4955 11.7 Persons cautioned by the police: by age and sex 1,3,4 England and Wales Thousands 1997 1998 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 Males Indictable offences All ages KEGA 143.3 142.9 126.1 109.7 103.8 104.4 109.8 110.0 129.9 147.6 148.5 10 and under 15 years2 KEGB 22.9 23.7 22.0 20.3 19.7 16.7 16.9 18.7 21.0 21.7 19.7 15 and under 18 years2 KEGC 32.0 32.0 28.7 25.0 24.5 23.3 24.1 25.9 28.0 30.2 30.0 18 and under 21 years KEGD 25.2 25.7 22.7 20.1 18.5 18.9 19.4 16.7 19.8 22.9 23.7 21 years and over KEGE 63.2 61.5 52.7 44.3 41.2 45.6 49.4 48.7 61.1 72.8 75.1 Summar y offences All ages KEGF 75.7 76.9 76.1 69.6 68.0 63.8 70.9 76.0 87.6 112.0 120.2 10 and under 15 years2 KEGG 9.9 10.6 11.7 12.0 12.7 10.3 10.9 12.6 15.5 17.9 17.8 15 and under 18 years2 KEGH 16.1 16.1 16.1 14.9 15.2 13.3 15.1 17.2 18.6 21.3 21.3 18 and under 21 years KEGI 12.9 13.2 13.0 11.9 11.0 11.0 12.4 12.3 12.2 15.0 16.4 21 years and over KEGJ 36.9 37.0 35.3 30.9 29.0 29.2 32.5 33.9 41.2 57.8 64.6 Females Indictable offences All ages KEGK 46.0 48.8 44.5 41.2 40.1 38.5 41.0 46.3 53.0 56.2 56.6 10 and under 15 years2 KEGL 9.2 11.1 9.8 10.0 10.1 8.4 8.6 10.6 12.2 12.5 12.6 15 and under 18 years2 KEGM 9.5 10.3 9.3 9.0 9.3 8.3 9.1 10.7 12.2 12.7 13.0 18 and under 21 years KEGN 5.7 5.9 5.7 5.2 4.9 4.8 4.9 5.2 5.8 6.2 6.3 21 years and over KEGO 21.5 21.4 19.6 17.0 15.9 17.0 18.4 19.9 22.8 24.7 24.8 Summar y offences All ages KEGP 17.0 19.2 9.4 18.5 18.0 18.6 20.2 23.5 28.5 34.2 37.6 10 and under 15 years2 KEGQ 1.7 2.1 2.5 2.8 2.9 2.7 3.0 3.9 5.1 5.6 5.7 15 and under 18 years2 KEGR 3.2 3.7 3.9 3.7 3.8 3.6 4.3 5.4 6.2 7.1 7.3 18 and under 21 years KEGS 2.3 2.6 2.7 2.5 2.3 2.4 2.7 2.9 3.3 4.1 4.7 21 years and over KEGT 9.9 10.8 10.3 9.6 9.0 9.8 10.2 11.3 13.9 17.4 20.0 1 See chapter text. 2 From 1 June 2000 the Crime and Disorder Act 1998 came into force nation- ally and removed the use of cautions for persons under 18 and replaced them with reprimands and final war nings. 3 These data are on the principal offence basis. 4 Every effor t is made to ensure that the figures presented are accurate and complete. How ever, it is impor tant to note that these data have been extracted from large administrative data systems generated by police forces. As a con- sequence, care should be taken to ensure data collection processes and their inevitable limitations are taken into account when those data are used. Source: Office for Criminal Justice Refor m:020 7035 4955 173 Crime and justice 11.8 Sentence or order passed on persons sentenced for indictable offences: by sex 1 England and Wales Magistrates’ courts and the Crown Court Percentages and thousands 1997 1998 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 Males Sentence or order Absolute discharge KEJB 0.7 0.7 0.6 0.6 0.6 0.8 0.9 0.8 0.7 0.7 0.7 Conditional discharge KEJC 15.5 15.3 15.0 14.1 13.4 12.4 13.0 12.2 11.9 11.3 12.2 Fine KEJF 28.2 28.4 27.7 25.7 24.5 23.9 24.0 20.9 19.4 17.4 16.2 Community rehabilitation order KEJD 10.0 10.0 10.1 10.1 10.7 10.6 10.1 9.5 5.6 0.8 0.5 Super vision order KEJE 2.7 2.7 2.7 2.4 2.3 2.1 1.8 2.0 2.1 2.3 2.4 Community punishment order KEJG 9.5 9.3 9.3 9.5 9.0 8.6 8.3 8.8 6.3 1.2 0.5 Attendance centre order KEJH 1.8 1.7 1.8 1.5 1.2 0.7 0.6 0.6 0.6 0.6 0.6 Community punishment and KIJW 3.7 3.8 3.7 3.6 2.6 2.6 2.6 2.8 2.1 0.5 0.4 rehabilitation order Curfew order LUJP 0.1 0.2 0.3 0.5 0.7 1.1 1.6 2.7 2.3 1.3 1.3 Reparation order SNFI .. .. .. 0.7 1.3 0.8 0.4 0.4 0.5 0.6 0.6 Action plan order SNFJ .. .. .. 0.9 1.7 1.1 0.7 0.8 0.8 0.8 0.8 Dr ug treatment and testing order SNFK .. .. .. 0.1 1.2 1.4 1.9 2.3 1.6 0.1 − Referral order SNFL .. .. .. .. .. 3.0 4.0 4.4 5.2 5.2 5.5 Community order2 GN7P .. .. .. .. .. .. .. .. 8.7 19.8 20.4 Suspended sentence order KEJL 0.8 0.7 0.6 0.7 0.6 0.5 0.5 0.6 1.7 6.7 8.6 Imprisonment Sec 90-92 LUJQ 0.3 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.1 Detention and training order LUJR .. .. .. 1.4 1.9 1.8 1.5 1.6 1.6 1.7 1.5 Young offender institution KEJK 6.1 6.0 6.2 5.2 4.5 4.2 3.6 3.8 3.7 3.6 3.8 Unsuspended imprisonment KEJM 17.9 18.2 18.7 19.9 20.0 20.9 20.6 21.5 21.2 20.4 19.9 Other sentence or order KEJN 3.0 2.6 3.1 3.1 3.4 3.3 3.5 4.1 3.9 4.4 4.0 Total number of males (thousands) = 100 per cent KEJA 275.4 292.4 291.3 277.1 274.6 285.6 282.3 267.5 259.4 258.4 265.8 Females Sentence or order Absolute discharge KEKB 0.8 0.7 0.7 0.6 0.6 0.9 1.0 0.8 0.8 0.7 0.8 Conditional discharge KEKC 29.4 28.7 26.9 24.9 23.9 22.0 22.5 21.8 20.7 20.1 20.8 Fine KEKF 21.8 21.3 20.8 20.1 18.6 17.9 18.5 16.7 15.2 12.8 12.1 Community rehabilitation order KEKD 19.1 19.1 19.4 19.6 19.1 19.2 17.0 15.4 9.0 1.4 0.5 Super vision order KEKE 2.9 3.1 2.9 2.8 2.7 2.1 2.1 2.1 2.4 2.5 2.6 Community punishment order KEKG 6.5 6.5 7.1 7.5 7.3 6.8 6.6 7.6 6.1 1.6 0.4 Attendance centre order KEKH 1.0 0.9 0.9 0.8 0.6 0.4 0.3 0.3 0.3 0.5 0.3 Community punishment and KIJX 3.2 3.4 3.3 3.0 2.1 2.1 1.8 1.9 1.5 0.5 0.2 rehabilitation order Curfew order LUJT 0.1 0.1 0.3 0.4 0.6 0.8 1.4 2.2 2.3 1.1 1.1 Reparation order SNFX .. .. .. 0.8 1.6 0.8 0.4 0.5 0.5 0.5 0.6 Action plan order SNFZ .. .. .. 1.0 2.0 1.2 0.8 0.8 1.0 0.9 0.9 Dr ug treatment and testing order SNGA .. .. .. 0.1 1.4 1.7 2.4 3.2 2.1 0.2 − Referral order SNGB .. .. .. .. .. 3.9 5.1 5.6 6.7 6.9 7.0 Community order2 GN7Q .. .. .. .. .. .. .. .. 9.9 23.3 24.5 Suspended sentence order KEKL 1.6 1.5 1.3 1.3 1.2 1.1 1.0 1.3 2.5 7.8 9.6 Imprisonment Sec 90-92 LUJU 0.1 .. 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.1 − − Detention and training order LUJV .. .. .. 0.6 0.8 0.8 0.7 0.7 0.8 0.7 0.8 Young offender institution KEKK 1.9 2.2 2.4 2.2 2.0 1.9 1.7 1.4 1.6 1.6 1.4 Unsuspended imprisonment KEKM 9.4 10.0 11.0 11.5 12.1 12.7 12.8 13.2 12.6 12.8 12.4 Other sentence or order KEKN 2.2 2.5 3.0 2.9 3.5 3.4 3.8 4.3 3.8 4.3 3.7 Total number of females (thousands) = 100 per cent KEKA 42.1 47.2 49.0 47.8 47.3 49.9 50.2 48.3 46.1 43.7 45.4 1 See chapter text. Ever y effor t is made to ensure that the figures presented are accurate and complete. How ever, it is impor tant to note that these data have been extracted from large administrative data systems generated by the courts and police forces. As a consequence, care should be taken to ensure data collection processes and their inevitable limitations are taken into account when those data are used. 2 The community order was introduced on 4 April 2005 and applies to offences committed on or after that date. Source: Office for Criminal Justice Refor m: 020 7035 4955 174 Crime and justice 11.9 Persons sentenced to life imprisonment or immediate custody: by sex and ageEngland and Wales Number of Persons 1997 1998 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 Life imprisonment1 Males All ages I28G 346 380 465 446 484 536 489 548 594 531 471 10 - 17 years I28D 24 11 26 19 28 21 11 15 27 16 23 18 - 20 years I28E 29 25 38 9 27 21 47 24 50 46 70 21 years and over I28F 293 344 401 418 429 494 431 509 517 469 378 Females All ages I28K 21 14 19 21 19 19 24 22 31 16 21 10 - 17 years I28H 3 1 3 2 1 1 − 1 1 − 3 18 - 20 years I28I 2 − 2 1 3 2 4 2 4 2 3 21 years and over I28J 16 13 14 18 15 16 20 19 26 14 15 All persons All ages I28O 367 394 484 467 503 555 513 570 625 547 492 10 - 17 years I28L 27 12 29 21 29 22 11 16 28 16 26 18 - 20 years I28M 31 25 40 10 30 23 51 26 54 48 73 21 years and over I28N 309 357 415 436 444 510 451 528 543 483 393 Immediate custody2 Males All ages JF7E 87 989 93 619 97 355 97 841 97 728 102 240 98 371 97 020 91 954 86 239 85 285 10 - 17 years JF7F 6 751 6 870 7 218 6 949 7 119 6 865 5 765 5 866 5 463 5 669 5 277 18 - 20 years JF7G 15 114 16 127 17 011 17 315 16 855 16 269 14 418 13 793 13 237 12 802 13 126 21 years and over JF7H 66 124 70 622 73 126 73 577 73 754 79 106 78 188 77 361 73 254 67 768 66 882 Females All ages JF7I 5 485 6 553 7 485 7 879 8 042 8 812 8 786 8 732 8 231 7 783 7 722 10 - 17 years JF7J 305 335 406 444 448 529 424 443 498 453 466 18 - 20 years JF7K 640 851 961 1 116 1 063 1 071 969 817 875 841 793 21 years and over JF7L 4 540 5 367 6 118 6 319 6 531 7 212 7 393 7 472 6 858 6 489 6 463 All persons All ages JF7M 93 474 100 172 104 840 105 720 105 770 111 052 107 157 105 752 100 185 94 022 93 007 10 - 17 years JF7N 7 056 7 205 7 624 7 393 7 567 7 394 6 189 6 309 5 961 6 122 5 743 18 - 20 years JF7O 15 754 16 978 17 972 18 431 17 918 17 340 15 387 14 610 14 112 13 643 13 919 21 years and over JF7P 70 664 75 989 79 244 79 896 80 285 86 318 85 581 84 833 80 112 74 257 73 345 1 Includes detention under the Pow ers of Criminal Courts (Sentencing) Act 2000, Secs 90-92 (Childrens and Young Persons Act 1993, Secs 53(1) & (2) prior to Aug 2000) (persons aged 10-17), custody for life under the Po wers of Criminal Courts (Sentencing) Act 2000, Secs 93 and 94 (1) (per- sons aged 18 - 20), mandatory life sentences under the Pow ers of Criminal Cour ts (Sentencing) Act 2000 Sec 109 (persons aged 18 and over) and immediate imprisonment (persons aged 21 and over). Indeterminate sentences for public protection under the Cr iminal Justice Act 2003 are excluded. 2 Excludes life and indeterminate sentences. Source: Office for Criminal Justice Refor m:020 8760 1404 175 Crime and justice 11.10 Receptions and average population in custodyEngland and Wales Numbers1 1997 1998 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 Receptions Type of inmate: Untr ied KEDA 62 066 64 697 64 572 54 892 53 467 58 708 58 696 54 556 55 455 55 809 55 305 Convicted, unsentenced KEDB 36 424 43 387 45 893 43 889 46 851 53 301 53 246 50 115 49 104 47 995 43 566 Sentenced KEDE 87 168 91 282 93 965 93 671 91 978 94 807 93 495 95 161 92 452 90 038 91 736 Immediate custodial sentence KEDF 80 832 85 908 90 238 91 195 90 523 93 615 92 245 93 326 90 414 88 134 90 261 Young offenders KEDG 18 743 19 599 21 020 21 333 20 969 20 236 18 179 18 264 17 819 17 985 19 022 Up to 12 months KEDH 11 867 12 942 14 330 14 639 14 234 12 891 11 850 11 855 11 610 11 526 12 295 12 months up to 4 years KEDJ 5 949 5 921 5 904 5 877 5 856 6 355 5 412 5 426 5 243 5 317 5 530 4 years up to and including life KEDL 927 736 786 817 879 990 917 983 966 1 142 1 197 Adults KFBO 62 089 66 309 69 218 69 862 69 554 73 379 74 066 75 062 72 595 70 149 71 239 Up to 12 months KEDV 38 702 42 513 45 662 46 759 46 146 47 870 48 962 49 814 48 190 45 768 46 706 12 months up to 4 years KEDW 17 546 18 100 17 751 17 290 17 116 18 313 17 968 17 988 17 397 16 970 17 233 4 years up to and including life KEDX 5 841 5 696 5 805 5 813 6 292 7 196 7 136 7 260 7 008 7 411 7 300 Committed in default of payment of a fine KEDY 6 336 5 374 3 727 2 476 1 455 1 192 1 250 1 835 1 876 1 904 1 475 Young offenders KEEA 555 568 366 216 138 110 116 155 162 118 92 Adults KAFQ 5 781 4 806 3 361 2 260 1 317 1 082 1 134 1 680 1 714 1 786 1 383 Non-cr iminal pr isoners KEDM 3 204 3 290 3 271 3 153 4 630 2 674 3 142 3 669 3 668 4 734 3 888 Immigration Act 1971 KEDN 2 122 2 348 2 443 2 455 4 035 2 093 2 457 3 041 3 093 4 073 3 347 Others KEDO 1 082 942 828 698 595 581 685 628 575 661 541 Average population Total in custody KEDP 61 114 65 298 64 771 64 602 66 301 70 861 73 038 74 657 75 979 78 150 80 395 Total in prison service establishments KFBQ 61 114 65 298 64 771 64 602 66 301 70 778 73 038 74 657 75 979 78 127 80 216 Police cells2 KFBN − − − − − 83 − − − 22 179 Untr ied KEDQ 8 453 8 157 7 947 7 098 6 924 7 727 7 862 7 735 8 088 8 293 8 273 Convicted, unsentenced KEDR 3 678 4 411 4 571 4 177 4 314 5 064 5 060 4 750 4 806 4 967 4 560 Sentenced KEDU 48 413 52 176 51 691 52 685 54 051 57 222 59 007 61 071 61 991 63 504 65 963 Immediate custodial sentence KFBR 48 272 52 045 51 596 52 620 54 006 57 184 58 959 61 012 61 925 63 429 65 533 Young offenders KFBS 7 821 8 490 8 336 8 435 8 558 8 777 8 421 8 290 8 239 8 535 9 188 Deter minate sentence I7IJ 7 707 8 363 8 197 8 288 8 408 8 616 8 262 8 123 8 030 8 141 8 502 Indeter minate sentence I7IL 114 127 139 147 150 161 159 167 209 394 683 Adults KFCO 40 451 43 556 43 261 44 185 45 448 48 408 50 536 52 721 53 686 54 894 56 776 Deter minate sentence I7IK 36 838 39 733 39 183 39 779 40 768 43 411 45 278 47 264 47 914 47 885 47 850 Indeter minate sentence I7IM 3 613 3 823 4 078 4 406 4 680 4 997 5 258 5 457 5 772 7 009 8 850 Committed in default of payment of a fine KFCS 141 131 95 64 45 37 48 59 71 82 79 Young offenders KFEW 13 15 9 4 6 2 3 4 3 3 3 Adults KFEX 128 116 86 59 39 35 45 54 68 79 76 Non-cr iminal pr isoners KEEB 572 554 558 641 1 012 847 1 107 1 100 1 087 1 355 1 420 Immigration Act 1971 KEEC 485 474 485 576 955 777 1 041 1 033 1 022 1 288 1 348 Others KEED 87 79 73 63 57 69 67 68 65 65 72 Accommodation3 I7IQ 56 329 61 253 62 369 63 436 63 757 64 232 66 104 67 576 69 443 70 585 73 618 1 The components do not always add up to the totals as they have been rounded independently. 2 Mostly untried prisoners. 3 In use Certified Normal Accommodation at 30 June every year. Source: Ministry of Justice: 020 7210 0638 176 Crime and justice 11.11 Prison population serving sentences: by age and offence 1,2 England and Wales Numbers Age in years 15 - 17 18 - 20 21 - 24 25 - 29 30 - 39 40 - 49 50 - 59 60 and over Total At 30 June 2002 Offences Males Total 1 986 5 821 9 722 10 196 15 415 6 630 2 832 1 365 53 967 Violence against the person 336 1 187 1 942 1 937 3 490 1 769 749 267 11 678 Sexual offences 58 167 262 406 1 347 1 241 996 794 5 270 Burglar y 396 1 130 2 159 2 331 2 379 448 58 15 8 917 Robber y 503 1 285 1 647 1 390 1 865 443 66 10 7 208 Theft, handling, fraud and forger y 302 570 1 055 1 105 1 416 480 213 62 5 203 Dr ugs offences 43 431 1 255 1 763 3 142 1 496 495 129 8 754 Other offences 275 875 1 195 1 103 1 555 640 205 73 5 921 Offences not known 72 174 207 162 222 113 50 15 1 016 Females Total 103 356 596 662 1 030 439 134 19 3 339 Violence against the person 27 67 73 85 163 84 33 6 538 Sexual offences - 1 - 1 11 6 3 1 23 Burglar y 9 37 58 54 68 12 1 - 239 Robber y 19 63 89 65 60 14 3 1 314 Theft, handling, fraud and forger y 22 56 103 139 168 68 20 4 581 Dr ugs offences 8 94 206 256 474 216 60 6 1 319 Other offences 12 32 52 50 73 34 9 1 262 Offences not known 6 7 16 13 13 5 4 - 63 At 30 June 2003 Offences Males Total 1 724 5 740 10 112 10 441 16 304 7 252 2 975 1 413 55 962 Violence against the person 310 1 257 2 112 2 068 3 733 1 932 780 290 12 482 Sexual offences 42 183 310 390 1 376 1 353 1 023 838 5 514 Burglar y 289 919 2 003 2 204 2 555 527 71 11 8 579 Robber y 436 1 370 1 910 1 546 2 022 514 69 12 7 879 Theft, handling, fraud and forger y 291 543 1 020 1 060 1 437 472 201 45 5 069 Dr ugs offences 43 452 1 256 1 791 3 215 1 579 528 127 8 993 Other offences 271 884 1 329 1 218 1 760 787 263 69 6 581 Offences not known 42 133 172 164 205 89 40 21 865 Females Total 57 305 670 702 1 100 492 123 28 3 477 Violence against the person 10 61 91 66 155 82 32 7 506 Sexual offences - - 2 1 11 7 3 2 26 Burglar y 1 24 64 60 77 12 2 - 240 Robber y 21 60 105 100 93 24 4 - 407 Theft, handling, fraud and forger y 10 56 117 128 199 70 18 11 609 Dr ugs offences 6 73 226 271 453 253 54 8 1 343 Other offences 7 27 58 66 108 39 6 - 311 Offences not known 2 3 8 10 5 4 4 - 36 At 30 June 2004 Offences Males Total 1 706 5 585 10 095 10 738 17 021 7 858 3 013 1 508 57 523 Violence against the person 326 1 353 2 247 2 272 3 965 2 107 799 304 13 373 Sexual offences 55 193 329 424 1 433 1 416 1 030 865 5 747 Burglar y 242 855 1 807 2 141 2 662 608 71 11 8 397 Robber y 449 1 254 1 865 1 691 2 127 583 70 17 8 056 Theft, handling, fraud and forger y 272 502 903 1 045 1 479 573 180 63 5 017 Dr ugs offences 51 471 1 383 1 789 3 258 1 615 537 150 9 256 Other offences 286 848 1 390 1 249 1 895 868 284 87 6 908 Offences not known 25 108 171 126 202 87 41 10 769 Females Total 58 300 632 727 1 056 507 152 20 3 453 Violence against the person 15 70 98 89 192 95 36 9 603 Sexual offences - - 3 3 8 7 4 2 27 Burglar y 6 19 59 83 56 22 3 - 247 Robber y 8 65 93 90 114 20 2 - 392 Theft, handling, fraud and forger y 11 28 100 140 171 67 25 1 543 Dr ugs offences 6 78 197 245 392 246 65 6 1 235 Other offences 11 37 75 72 108 44 13 2 361 Offences not known 2 3 8 7 15 7 4 - 46 177 Crime and justice 11.11 Prison population serving sentences: by age and offence 1,2 England and Wales continued Numbers Age in years 15 - 17 18 - 20 21 - 24 25 - 29 30 - 39 40 - 49 50 - 59 60 and over Total At 30 June 2005 Offences Males Total 1 782 5 595 9 937 10 969 16 843 8 731 3 256 1 594 58 707 Violence against the person 366 1 493 2 553 2 553 4 015 2 402 840 319 14 541 Sexual offences 65 186 397 505 1 436 1 552 1 084 922 6 147 Burglar y 285 719 1 559 1 947 2 570 669 78 17 7 844 Robber y 422 1 307 1 819 1 705 2 035 649 83 15 8 035 Theft, handling, fraud and forger y 240 433 858 1 074 1 449 650 238 55 4 997 Dr ugs offences 76 491 1 332 1 834 3 263 1 741 544 148 9 429 Other offences 310 870 1 306 1 245 1 902 987 360 99 7 079 Offences not known 18 96 113 106 173 81 29 19 635 Females Total 55 269 614 680 1 073 585 179 24 3 479 Violence against the person 23 68 109 85 190 114 40 9 638 Sexual offences - 2 3 4 12 8 7 3 39 Burglar y 4 18 50 62 79 23 3 - 239 Robber y 16 59 61 82 102 20 3 - 343 Theft, handling, fraud and forger y 4 35 105 119 202 88 27 3 583 Dr ugs offences 3 54 195 255 366 268 84 9 1 234 Other offences 5 30 84 68 117 56 14 - 374 Offences not known - 3 7 5 5 8 1 - 29 At 30 June 2006 Offences Males Total 1 814 5 716 9 612 11 349 16 828 9 349 3 511 1 719 59 898 Violence against the person 381 1 563 2 616 2 977 4 109 2 609 935 348 15 537 Sexual offences 67 213 452 560 1 497 1 683 1 118 971 6 561 Burglar y 275 707 1 363 1 838 2 554 715 97 15 7 563 Robber y 486 1 413 1 739 1 674 1 975 706 91 16 8 100 Theft, handling, fraud and forger y 200 451 830 1 093 1 598 707 214 54 5 147 Dr ugs offences 68 492 1 232 1 913 3 153 1 829 623 174 9 484 Other offences 327 835 1 326 1 231 1 838 1 040 406 129 7 129 Offences not known 12 43 55 64 105 60 28 10 378 Females Total 50 271 551 707 1 094 604 189 39 3 506 Violence against the person 11 75 111 101 205 118 48 9 678 Sexual offences 1 3 2 2 8 13 5 3 37 Burglar y 7 13 39 63 80 24 2 - 228 Robber y 17 48 67 76 86 18 2 - 315 Theft, handling, fraud and forger y 3 30 97 171 232 106 24 7 671 Dr ugs offences 4 62 158 217 354 253 88 17 1 163 Other offences 7 36 61 72 120 67 19 3 385 Offences not known 1 5 5 4 9 5 1 - 30 At 30 June 2007 Offences Males Total 1 827 6 354 9 860 11 653 16 606 10 092 3 823 1 973 62 188 Violence against the person 402 1 772 2 927 3 183 4 337 2 846 1 063 399 16 929 Sexual offences 73 276 487 675 1 555 1 909 1 202 1 112 7 287 Burglar y 281 817 1 334 1 865 2 492 812 109 13 7 723 Robber y 495 1 558 1 855 1 716 1 928 774 96 14 8 437 Theft, handling, fraud and forger y 194 426 677 1 044 1 478 711 246 67 4 844 Dr ugs offences 71 546 1 285 1 858 3 002 1 908 689 210 9 569 Other offences 294 908 1 237 1 242 1 731 1 087 401 152 7 051 Offences not known 17 51 59 69 83 47 18 5 348 Females Total 56 280 475 662 1 011 610 202 49 3 345 Violence against the person 20 99 113 111 170 117 47 11 687 Sexual offences - 1 3 7 16 15 4 2 48 Burglar y 2 11 28 56 76 23 1 - 197 Robber y 13 54 53 78 82 27 2 1 311 Theft, handling, fraud and forger y 7 29 68 128 211 111 37 10 601 Dr ugs offences 3 42 124 201 335 230 90 19 1 044 Other offences 9 45 75 76 115 77 20 6 423 Offences not known 2 - 10 5 6 10 2 - 35 1 The data presented in this table are drawn from administrative IT systems. Where figures in the table have been rounded to the nearest whole number, the rounded components do not always add to the totals, which are calcu- lated and rounded independently. Reconciliation exercises with published Home Office figures may demonstrate differences due to rounded compo- nents. A programme of wor k is currently being undertaken to audit the quality of the data and to identify prior ities for improvements. 2 Excludes persons committed in default of payment of a fine. Source: Ministry of Justice: 020 7210 8500 178 Crime and justice 11.12 Expenditure on prisonsEngland and Wales Operating cost and total capital employed, years ending 31 March £ thousand 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 /02 /03 /04 /05 /06 /07 /08 Expenditure Staff costs KWUV 1 138 400 1 259 502 1 364 193 1 439 882 1 498 446 1 586 126 1 646 757 Accommodation costs KXCO 193 100 200 000 194 000 185 400 150 270 138 322 144 170 Other operating costs KXCP 706 100 756 198 653 007 694 618 528 529 498 913 511 688 Depreciation KXCQ 128 100 132 600 129 600 143 800 7 974 11 044 12 135 Cost of capital KXCR 284 900 292 700 164 400 170 300 279 905 −610 Total expenditure KXCS 2 450 600 2 641 000 2 505 200 2 634 000 2 185 498 2 235 310 2 314 140 Income Contr ibutions from industries KXCT −11 600 −10 100 −11 000 −10 600 −11 154 −7 698 −7 079 Other operating income KXCU −13 100 −15 500 −21 000 −38 400 −41 323 −45 411 −43 566 Income from Other Government Departments1 GDPM −180 600 −210 200 −368 000 −381 500 −302 549 −245 917 −205 524 Total income KXCV −205 300 −235 800 −400 000 −430 500 −355 026 −299 026 −256 169 Net operating costs KXCW 2 245 300 2 405 200 2 105 200 2 203 500 1 830 472 1 936 284 2 057 971 Total capital employed KXCX 4 859 600 4 821 500 5 228 600 5 116 700 5 716 −52 207 −42 577 1 Income from the Youth Justice Board (a non-departmental public body of the Home Office) for the provision of juvenile custody within the Prison Ser- vice, Depar tment for Education and Skills for the provision of education ser- vices and Department of Health and PCTs for the provision of healthcare. Source: NOMS Agency: 020 7217 5213 179 Crime and justice 11.13 Crimes and offences recorded by the police: by crime group 1 Scotland Thousands 1998 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 20044 2005 2006 2007 /99 /00 /01 /02 /03 /04 /05 /06 /07 /08 Non-sexual crimes of violence against the person BEBC 19.8 15.8 14.9 15.7 16.1 15.1 14.7 13.8 14.1 12.9 Ser ious assault, etc2 KAFS 6.7 7.3 6.9 7.5 7.6 7.5 7.8 7.2 7.5 6.9 Robber y KAFU 5.0 4.9 4.3 4.6 4.6 4.2 3.7 3.6 3.6 3.1 Other KAFV 3.0 3.6 3.6 3.5 3.8 3.5 3.2 3.0 3.0 3.0 Crimes involving indecency BEBD 7.1 5.8 5.8 6.0 6.6 6.8 7.3 6.6 6.8 6.6 Rape and attempted rape1 OXBQ 0.8 0.8 0.7 0.8 0.9 1.0 1.1 1.2 1.1 1.1 Indecent assault1 OXBR 1.3 1.1 1.0 1.2 1.4 1.4 1.5 1.5 1.7 1.7 Lewd and indecent behaviour KAFY 2.9 2.3 2.4 2.4 2.8 2.6 2.8 2.7 2.6 2.6 Other KAFZ 2.1 1.7 1.6 1.6 1.6 1.7 1.9 1.2 1.4 1.3 Crimes involving dishonesty BEBE 276.9 275.6 253.3 242.8 224.8 211.0 210.4 187.8 183.7 166.7 Housebreaking3 KAGB 55.8 52.9 47.7 45.5 40.6 36.4 35.0 31.3 30.6 25.4 Theft by opening lockfast places KAGC 12.1 11.6 10.6 8.2 7.8 7.4 7.9 8.3 7.4 6.4 Theft from a motor vehicle (OLP) EPI4 39.5 38.0 32.0 32.7 30.4 26.8 20.4 16.5 16.1 15.2 Theft of a motor vehicle KAGD 29.3 28.9 25.6 23.1 20.9 17.6 15.6 14.0 15.0 12.1 Shoplifting KAGE 30.8 32.1 32.3 31.6 28.3 27.9 28.5 28.2 28.8 29.2 Other theft KAGF 80.1 81.2 76.6 76.0 73.2 72.5 77.6 72.1 70.2 64.6 Fr aud KAGG 18.4 20.6 20.0 17.4 15.8 15.3 18.3 11.1 9.3 8.4 Other KAGH 11.1 10.3 8.4 8.4 7.9 7.0 7.1 6.3 6.4 5.3 Fire-raising, vandalism, etc BEBF 77.6 81.2 85.8 95.0 97.7 103.8 128.5 127.9 129.7 118.0 Fire-raising KAGJ 2.5 2.3 2.4 2.9 3.8 4.2 4.7 4.9 5.0 4.6 Vandalism, etc KAGK 75.2 78.9 83.4 92.0 93.8 99.6 123.9 123.0 124.8 113.4 Other crimes BEBG 52.6 57.1 58.9 66.8 73.2 77.5 77.2 81.9 84.9 81.3 Cr imes against public justice KAGM 17.7 18.4 18.6 20.9 22.7 25.8 25.6 27.7 32.1 31.4 Handling offensive weapons2 KAFT 7.1 8.1 8.1 9.0 9.4 9.3 9.5 9.6 10.1 9.0 Dr ugs KAGN 32.8 30.4 32.1 36.8 40.9 42.3 41.8 44.2 42.4 40.7 Other KAGO 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.1 0.2 0.2 0.2 0.3 0.4 0.3 Total crimes KAGQ 434.1 435.5 418.5 426.2 418.3 414.2 438.1 417.8 419.3 385.5 Miscellaneous offences BEBH 153.2 151.9 154.8 163.4 169.6 181.0 214.3 219.5 232.4 224.3 Minor assault KAGS 51.6 54.6 54.1 55.4 55.0 57.4 73.7 72.3 78.2 73.5 Breach of the peace KAGT 71.7 71.3 70.2 72.7 74.7 77.9 90.0 89.6 93.4 90.3 Dr unkenness KAGU 8.4 7.6 7.8 7.8 7.3 7.5 7.2 7.0 6.7 6.7 Other KAGV 21.6 18.4 22.8 27.6 32.6 38.2 43.4 50.6 54.2 53.7 Motor vehicle offences BEBI 367.2 347.5 340.1 362.5 350.1 435.0 424.3 380.5 375.1 347.7 Dangerous and careless driving KAGX 15.8 13.2 12.0 12.2 12.7 12.0 13.1 13.0 13.6 13.0 Dr unk dr iving KAGY 10.6 10.9 10.8 11.5 11.8 11.6 11.1 11.3 11.7 10.7 Speeding KAGZ 119.7 123.4 113.9 126.8 117.2 199.2 210.1 167.7 162.9 137.2 Unlawful use of a motor vehicle KAHA 76.0 80.7 84.3 94.6 99.5 99.5 76.7 75.1 73.1 73.7 Vehicle defect offences KAHB 63.8 48.0 46.8 45.5 46.5 37.2 27.0 23.9 21.2 22.3 Other KAHC 81.3 71.2 73.3 77.9 66.9 75.4 86.3 89.4 92.6 90.8 Total offences KAHD 520.5 499.4 496.1 532.0 524.1 615.9 638.6 600.0 607.4 571.9 Total crimes and offences BEBB 954.6 934.9 913.5 952.4 937.8 1 030.1 1 076.7 1 017.7 1 026.6 957.4 1 See chapter text. 2 Includes murder, attempted murder, culpable homicide and serious assault. 3 Includes dwellings, non-dwellings and other premises. 4 The introduction of the Scottish Crime Recording Standard on 1 April 2004 has increased the number of minor crimes recorded, such as minor crimes of theft, vandalism, petty assault and breach of the peace. Source: The Scottish Government Justice Department: 0131 244 2635 180 Crime and justice 11.14 Persons with a charge proved: by crime group 1 Scotland Numbers 1997 1998 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 20073 /98 /99 /00 /01 /02 /03 /04 /05 /06 /07 /08 Non-sexual crimes of violence KEHC 2 039 2 000 2 003 1 976 2 092 2 381 2 596 2 427 2 455 2 441 2 723 Homicide KEHD 104 92 105 100 103 99 131 143 111 118 129 Ser ious assault, etc KEHE 1 039 1 036 1 053 1 089 1 171 1 360 1 475 1 374 1 560 1 480 1 721 Robber y KEHG 666 652 659 603 627 682 689 610 509 527 539 Other violence KEHH 230 220 186 184 191 240 301 300 275 316 334 Cr imes of indecency KEHI 1 329 1 280 790 633 614 562 666 810 853 862 785 Rape and attempted rape HFVU 55 58 48 52 67 55 58 70 61 58 48 Indecent assault KEHJ 91 83 84 60 48 65 93 87 84 81 116 Lewd and libidinous practices KEHK 343 320 302 256 298 273 297 321 319 312 247 Other indecency KEHL 840 819 356 265 201 169 218 332 389 411 374 Cr imes of dishonesty KEHM 25 272 24 726 22 652 20 571 21 536 21 700 19 887 19 665 18 045 18 447 17 736 Housebreaking KEHN 3 174 3 071 2 860 2 676 2 672 2 752 2 508 2 373 2 074 2 025 1 868 Theft by opening lockfast places KEHO 1 940 1 770 1 614 1 504 1 478 1 448 1 288 1 194 951 911 942 Theft of motor vehicle KEHP 2 006 1 882 1 536 1 426 1 386 1 486 1 268 1 099 985 1 028 932 Shoplifting KEHQ 7 313 7 559 7 753 7 345 8 366 8 826 8 123 8 427 8 162 8 548 8 407 Other theft KEHR 5 866 5 796 5 026 4 303 4 234 3 783 3 521 3 551 3 187 3 303 3 138 Fr aud KEHS 1 992 1 920 1 595 1 448 1 479 1 459 1 444 1 355 1 245 1 180 1 165 Other dishonesty KEHT 2 981 2 728 2 268 1 869 1 921 1 946 1 735 1 666 1 441 1 452 1 284 Fire-raising, vandalism, etc KEHU 4 871 4 591 3 979 3 942 4 051 4 212 4 759 5 024 4 998 5 437 5 350 Fire-raising KEHV 112 125 102 109 125 147 169 192 192 251 223 Vandalism, etc KEHW 4 759 4 466 3 877 3 833 3 926 4 065 4 590 4 832 4 806 5 186 5 127 Other crime KEHX 14 551 13 698 12 888 12 558 13 823 13 954 15 453 16 800 16 968 19 833 20 191 Cr ime against public justice KFBK 5 096 4 776 4 589 4 929 5 257 5 048 5 290 5 767 5 753 7 206 8 028 Handling offensive weapons KEHF 2 173 2 033 2 118 2 340 2 633 2 771 2 875 3 447 3 500 3 550 3 418 Dr ugs offences KFBL 7 236 6 861 6 158 5 279 5 913 6 111 7 258 7 555 7 606 8 874 8 477 Other KFBM 46 28 23 10 20 24 30 31 109 203 268 Total crimes KEHB 48 062 46 295 42 312 39 680 42 116 42 809 43 361 44 726 43 319 47 020 46 785 Miscellaneous offences KEHZ 42 051 35 024 29 505 28 651 30 152 32 062 34 536 37 492 39 679 42 278 41 143 Common assault KEIA 12 441 11 677 10 749 10 270 10 823 11 745 12 317 13 574 14 427 15 441 15 460 Breach of the peace KEIB 19 355 17 156 14 023 13 031 13 950 14 384 15 050 16 172 16 901 18 111 17 410 Dr unkenness KEIC 937 626 454 430 374 370 418 311 293 261 235 Other miscellaneous offences KEID 9 318 5 565 4 279 4 920 5 005 5 563 6 751 7 435 8 058 8 465 8 038 Motor vehicle offences KEIE 55 456 51 638 51 603 40 264 44 821 47 956 50 622 47 515 45 203 45 065 45 148 Dangerous and careless driving KEIF 4 577 3 764 3 431 2 561 3 319 3 628 4 118 3 810 3 621 3 773 3 963 Dr unk dr iving KEIG 8 173 7 290 7 366 6 265 6 538 9 508 8 158 8 001 7 970 8 066 7 812 Speeding2 KEIH 12 220 12 971 15 293 9 427 9 988 9 832 12 700 13 546 12 273 13 434 14 114 Unlawful use of vehicle KEII 20 052 18 662 16 950 15 987 18 553 19 192 19 563 16 696 14 711 13 449 13 569 Vehicle defect offences KEIJ 3 198 2 470 2 075 1 302 1 252 1 510 1 859 1 791 1 653 1 709 2 298 Other motor vehicle offences KEIK 7 236 6 481 6 488 4 722 5 171 4 286 4 224 3 671 4 975 4 634 3 392 Total offences KEHY 101 272 90 879 85 792 73 526 79 482 84 963 90 253 85 007 84 882 87 343 86 291 Total crimes and offences KEHA 149 334 137 174 128 104 113 206 121 598 127 772 133 614 129 733 128 201 134 363 133 076 1 See chapter text. Data as at 28 April 2009. 2 Includes motorway and clearway offences. 3 Figures for 2007-08 for some categories dealt with by the High Court - includ- ing homicide, rape and major drug cases - may be underestimated slightly due to late recording of disposals on SCRO. Source: Scottish Government Justice Department: 0131 244 2229 11.15 Persons with a charge proved: by cour t procedure 1,2 Scotland Numbers 1997 1998 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 /98 /99 /00 /01 /02 /03 /04 /05 /06 /07 /08 Cour t procedure High Court3 KEIQ 1 105 1 043 1 174 1 092 1 125 1 194 1 217 974 882 858 804 Sher iff Cour t KEIU 78 668 74 484 70 541 65 714 72 021 80 117 80 155 80 866 79 956 85 185 85 096 Distr ict Cour t4,5 KEIV 57 388 50 784 46 052 38 422 38 484 41 516 47 144 47 891 47 358 48 319 47 176 Stipendiar y Magistrate Court4 KEIW 8 406 6 646 5 652 3 365 5 455 .. .. .. .. .. .. Total called to court6 KEIZ 145 569 132 957 123 420 108 595 117 089 122 827 128 519 129 733 128 201 134 363 133 076 1 See chapter text. 2 All figures are now repor ted as financial years. 3 Including cases remitted to the High Court from the Sheriff Court. Figure for 2007/08 may be an underestimate due to late recording of disposals on the Scottish Criminal History System. 4 Distr ict Cour t figures from 2002/03 include the Stipendiary Magistrate Court. 5 Figure for 2007/08 includes Justice of the Peace courts in Lothian & Borders from 10 March 2008. 6 Includes court type not known. Source: Scottish Government Justice Department: 0131 244 2229 181 Crime and justice 11.16 Persons with charge proved: by main penalty 1,2 Scotland Numbers 1997 1998 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 /98 /99 /00 /01 /02 /03 /04 /05 /06 /07 /08 Main penalty Restr iction of liberty order3 ZBRE .. 106 196 152 166 656 879 1 097 1 136 1 179 1 151 Super vised attendance order4 ZBRF 56 31 37 5 11 13 18 33 99 112 129 Dr ug treatment and testing order5 OEWA .. .. 5 117 286 409 610 713 758 865 817 Absolute discharge KEXA 508 403 368 364 415 385 435 403 401 411 427 Admonition or caution KEXB 14 367 13 442 12 188 11 203 11 702 12 360 12 934 13 744 14 175 15 967 15 955 Probation KEXC 6 278 6 824 6 542 6 654 7 708 8 451 8 137 8 623 8 785 8 612 8 984 Remit to children’s hear ing KEXD 208 176 120 116 158 230 196 221 260 313 259 Community service order KEXE 5 237 4 811 4 254 4 272 4 323 4 719 4 298 4 849 5 195 5 305 5 593 Fine KEXF 102 617 91 393 84 255 70 683 76 217 78 541 84 327 83 237 80 723 83 445 81 742 Compensation order KEXG 1 288 1 238 1 151 1 076 1 142 1 347 1 767 1 695 1 471 1 375 1 313 Insanity, hospital, guardianship order KYAN 154 125 136 116 103 101 129 95 115 65 20 Pr ison KEXI 11 028 10 635 10 609 10 430 11 437 12 427 11 960 12 307 12 153 13 449 13 530 Young offenders’ institution KEXJ 3 804 3 749 3 546 3 394 3 407 3 162 2 801 2 685 2 902 3 241 3 130 Detention of child KEXM 24 24 13 13 14 25 24 20 24 24 26 Total persons with charge proved6 KEXO 145 569 132 957 123 420 108 595 117 089 122 827 128 549 129 733 128 201 134 363 133 076 1 See chapter text. 2 All figures are now repor ted as financial years. 3 A community sentence introduced by Section 5 of the Crime and Punish- ment (Scotland) Act 1995 and available on a pilot basis to 3 Scottish sheriff cour ts since August 1998. This sentence was made available to High Cour t, Sher iff Cour ts and Stipendiary Magistrates court from 1 May 2002. 4 The pilot scheme under the Crime and Punishment (S) Act 1995, where fines for 16 & 17 year olds were replaced by super vised attendance orders, was discontinued in December 1999. The majority of supervised atten- dance orders recorded from the year 2000-01 onwards were disposals re- lating to the breach of an existing order. 5 Drug treatment and testing orders are new measures made available on a pilot basis to the High Court and to Sheriff Courts for residents in Glasgow (from October 1999), Fife (from July 2000) and Aberdeen/Aberdeenshire (from De- cember 2001). They are now available to all Sheriff courts and the High Court. 6 Totals from 2002/03 include a small number of cases where penalty is un- known. Source: Scottish Government Justice Department: 0131 244 2229 11.17 Persons with charge proved 1: by age and sex Scotland Numbers 1997 1998 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 /98 /99 /00 /01 /02 /03 /04 /05 /06 /07 /08 Males KEWA 124 691 114 884 106 654 92 919 100 874 104 312 107 932 108 460 107 801 113 465 112 349 Under 16 KEWB 134 112 75 56 80 129 96 107 133 121 155 16 to 20 KEWC 29 163 27 399 24 671 21 973 23 701 23 948 23 454 23 098 24 051 25 513 24 254 21 to 30 KEWD 48 751 43 599 40 048 35 251 38 441 39 405 40 053 39 336 38 078 40 389 41 076 Over 30 KEWE 45 643 42 857 41 047 34 957 38 362 40 811 44 324 45 913 45 536 47 440 46 864 Age not known KEWF 1 000 917 813 682 290 19 5 6 3 2 − Females KEWG 20 158 17 405 16 188 15 302 15 871 18 160 20 120 20 775 20 039 20 598 20 477 Under 16 KEWH 14 2 5 10 4 5 17 18 8 9 3 16 to 20 KEWI 3 314 3 252 3 089 2 768 2 742 2 840 2 927 2 891 2 929 3 255 3 287 21 to 30 KEWJ 8 004 6 872 6 219 5 833 6 200 6 843 7 494 7 652 7 387 7 397 7 355 Over 30 KEWK 8 411 6 971 6 614 6 448 6 854 8 468 9 680 10 214 9 715 9 935 9 832 Age not known KEWL 415 308 261 243 71 4 2 − − 2 − Males and Females KEWM 144 851 132 298 122 858 108 279 116 768 122 484 128 068 129 253 127 848 134 069 132 835 Under 16 KEWN 148 114 80 66 84 134 113 125 141 130 158 16 to 20 KEWO 32 477 30 652 27 761 24 746 26 444 26 790 26 381 25 989 26 981 28 768 27 541 21 to 30 KEWP 56 757 50 473 46 272 41 094 44 652 46 252 47 556 46 993 45 468 47 786 48 434 Over 30 KEWQ 54 054 49 829 47 665 41 437 45 226 49 285 54 011 56 140 55 255 57 381 56 702 Age not known KEWR 1 415 1 230 1 080 936 363 23 7 6 3 4 − Companies KEWS 718 659 562 316 320 343 451 480 353 294 241 Total persons with charge proved2 KEWT 145 569 132 957 123 420 108 595 117 089 122 827 128 519 129 733 128 201 134 363 133 076 1 See chapter text. 2 Includes sex unknown. Source: Scottish Government Justice Department: 0131 244 2229 182 Crime and justice 11.18 Penal establishments: average daily population and receptionsScotland Numbers 1998 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 /99 /00 /01 /02 /03 /04 /05 /06 /07 /08 Average daily population Male KEPB 5 830 5 765 5 676 5 929 6 193 6 307 6 447 6 523 6 830 7 005 Female KEPC 199 210 207 257 282 314 332 334 353 371 Total KEPA 6 029 5 975 5 883 6 186 6 475 6 621 6 779 6 857 7 183 7 376 Analysis by type of custody Remand KEPD 971 976 881 1 019 1 247 1 246 1 216 1 242 1 567 1 560 Persons under sentence: total KEPE 5 056 4 997 5 001 5 165 5 226 5 375 5 561 5 614 5 615 5 815 Adult prisoners KEPF 4 347 4 317 4 346 4 537 4 624 4 802 5 001 4 989 4 970 5 130 Young offenders KEPI 708 679 655 628 601 573 560 625 645 685 Persons recalled from super vision/licence1 KEPN 78 100 145 202 250 310 356 400 519 614 Others1 KEPO 21 28 36 37 6 6 5 1 − − Persons sentenced by cour t mar tial1 KEPP − 2 − − − − 1 − − − Civil prisoners1 KEPQ 1 1 1 1 2 − 1 1 1 1 Receptions to penal establishments Remand KEPR 15 713 14 626 14 062 15 725 19 198 18 963 18 892 19 593 23 181 22 491 Male KEPS 14 527 13 450 13 042 14 402 17 455 17 111 17 085 17 796 21 129 20 256 Female KEPT 1 186 1 176 1 020 1 323 1 743 1 852 1 807 1 797 2 052 2 235 Persons under sentence: total KEPU 22 376 20 336 19 136 18 953 20 084 19 357 18 584 19 477 20 403 18 227 Male KEPV 20 952 19 125 17 953 17 755 18 779 18 013 17 272 18 161 19 018 17 011 Female KEPW 1 424 1 211 1 183 1 198 1 305 1 344 1 312 1 316 1 385 1 216 Impr isoned: Adults: directly KEPX 9 887 9 217 8 943 9 470 10 571 10 255 10 299 10 746 11 684 11 846 in default of fine2 KEPY 7 907 7 030 6 450 5 882 6 081 6 063 5 404 5 442 5 265 3 208 Sentenced to young offenders’ institution: directly KEQA 2 824 2 582 2 436 2 312 2 207 1 949 1 908 2 170 2 286 2 359 in default of fine2 KEQB 1 606 1 328 1 116 1 109 1 016 825 694 771 698 402 Persons recalled from supervision/licence3 JYYD 152 179 191 180 209 265 279 348 470 412 Persons sentenced by cour t mar tial KEQH 2 3 2 2 3 1 5 − − 1 Civil prisoners2 KEQI 10 17 10 8 11 10 7 4 4 11 1 Persons recalled from supervision/licence and others are included in per- sons under sentence. Persons sentenced by cour t mar tial and civil prison- ers are not included in persons under sentence. 2 Includes in default of compensation orders. 3 Now covers all recalls from supervised release orders. Source: The Scottish Government Justice Department: 0131 244 8740 11.19 Expenditure on penal establishments 1 Scotland Years ended 31 March £ thousand 1997 1998 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 /98 /99 /00 /01 /02 /03 /04 /05 /06 /07 /08 Depar tmental Expenditure Manpower and Associated Services KPHC 137 890 144 660 170 347 160 242 172 490 168 593 169 784 181 931 200 742 199 854 206 298 Pr isoner and Associated Costs KPHD 16 313 18 891 22 930 23 501 24 652 23 363 51 070 42 767 28 582 41 821 29 408 Capital Expenditure KPHE 22 136 23 697 28 918 24 283 24 955 36 519 34 617 72 812 70 406 81 818 53 564 Gross Expenditure KPHF 176 339 187 248 222 195 208 026 222 097 228 475 255 471 297 510 299 730 323 493 289 270 Less Receipts KPHG 2 810 8 160 6 668 8 380 8 194 3 485 3 298 3 312 2 872 2 178 2 034 Net Departmental Expenditure KPHH 173 529 179 088 215 527 199 646 213 903 224 990 252 173 294 198 296 858 321 315 287 236 Plus Annually Managed Expenditure Capital Charges DSJI .. .. .. .. 31 341 40 432 41 728 48 497 52 840 41 816 59 498 Total Net Expenditure DSNX 173 529 179 088 215 527 199 646 245 244 265 422 293 901 342 695 349 698 363 131 346 734 1 See chapter text. Source: The Scottish Government Justice Department: 0131 244 2225 183 Crime and justice 11.20 Recorded crime statistics: by offence group 1 Nor thern Ireland Thousands Old counting rules New counting rules 1995 1996 1997 1998 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 /99 /00 /01 /02 /03 /04 /05 /06 /07 /08 Violence against the person RVCP 5.2 5.6 5.2 RVCQ 18.5 21.4 21.4 26.1 28.5 29.0 29.3 31.0 31.8 29.6 Sexual offences RVCR 1.7 1.7 1.4 RVCS 1.6 1.3 1.2 1.4 1.5 1.8 1.7 1.7 1.8 1.8 Burglar y RVCT 16.5 16.1 14.3 RVCU 15.5 16.1 15.8 17.1 18.7 16.4 13.4 12.8 11.6 11.7 Robber y RVCV 1.5 1.7 1.7 RVCW 1.4 1.4 1.8 2.2 2.5 2.0 1.5 1.7 1.6 1.1 Theft RVCX 33.5 32.8 29.5 RVCY 35.4 37.0 36.9 41.7 41.9 35.7 31.1 29.5 27.8 24.7 Fr aud and forger y RVCZ 4.9 4.1 3.8 RVDA 6.8 7.9 8.0 8.6 8.8 6.3 5.2 5.1 4.5 2.8 Cr iminal damage RVDB 3.8 4.8 4.7 RVDC 27.7 31.2 32.3 40.0 36.6 32.4 31.4 34.8 36.3 30.9 Offences against the state RVDD 0.3 0.4 0.5 RVDE 0.6 0.7 0.8 1.2 1.8 1.3 1.2 1.3 1.3 1.1 Other notifiable offences RVDF 1.5 1.2 1.1 RVDG 1.7 2.1 1.7 1.4 2.4 3.2 3.3 5.3 4.5 4.7 of which drug offences RVDH 1.4 1.1 1.0 RVDI 1.4 1.7 1.5 1.1 1.9 2.6 2.6 2.9 2.4 2.7 Total RVDR 68.8 68.5 62.2 RVDS 109.1 119.1 119.9 139.8 142.5 128.0 118.1 123.2 121.1 108.5 1 See chapter text. Source: The Police Service of Norther n Ireland 11.21 Persons found guilty at all courts: by offence group 1 Nor thern Ireland Numbers 1996 1997 1998 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 Violence against the person KYCT 1 597 1 594 1 596 1 699 1 858 1 621 1 790 1 965 2 012 2 009 2 296 Sexual offences KEVG 184 130 128 90 130 112 84 108 137 136 161 Burglar y KYBW 801 715 647 703 703 496 595 602 620 557 532 Robber y KYBX 161 166 134 129 122 121 152 192 159 135 149 Theft KYBY 2 765 2 596 2 342 1 995 2 111 1 831 1 695 1 803 1 819 1 819 1 728 Fr aud and forger y KYBZ 467 491 426 476 403 398 362 314 359 330 333 Cr iminal damage KYCA 1 076 1 163 1 043 931 1 060 917 957 1 034 1 094 1 168 1 295 Offences against the state KYCB 147 165 198 178 174 158 215 274 252 270 348 Other indictable2 KYCC 899 739 936 943 700 495 453 527 636 722 793 Total indictable3 KYCD 8 097 7 759 7 450 7 144 7 261 6 149 6 303 6 819 7 088 7 146 7 635 Summar y4 KYCE 4 402 4 435 4 062 3 598 3 967 3 735 3 453 3 514 3 622 3 575 3 645 Motor ing5 KYCF 18 177 18 770 15 369 15 782 15 390 14 466 14 344 16 342 17 215 15 534 15 083 All offences KYCG 30 676 30 964 26 881 26 524 26 618 24 350 24 100 26 675 27 925 26 255 26 363 1 See chapter text. 2 1998 and 1999 figures include ’dangerous driving’ (a triable-either-way offence). 3 From 2000, includes ’indictable-only’ motoring offences. 4 Excludes motoring offences. 5 Prior to 2000, includes all motoring offences (except for note 2 above). From 2000, includes summary and triable-either-way motor ing offences. Source: Norther n Ireland Office: 028 9052 7157 11.22 Juveniles found guilty at all courts: 1 by offence group Nor thern Ireland Numbers 1996 1997 1998 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 Violence against the person KYCH 75 49 97 73 77 66 82 75 78 146 152 Sexual offences KAHF 4 8 12 12 4 1 6 5 7 9 8 Burglar y KYCI 137 124 108 117 125 73 77 89 66 113 81 Robber y KYCJ 13 18 4 7 15 8 14 10 6 8 11 Theft KYCK 338 334 304 227 254 244 212 173 183 291 202 Fr aud and forger y KYCL 14 11 4 10 2 9 3 7 2 6 7 Cr iminal damage KYCM 121 136 139 102 143 152 132 162 129 241 240 Offences against the state KYCN 6 10 11 12 8 10 20 26 18 19 40 Other indictable2 KYCO 24 10 20 17 10 12 7 19 22 46 44 Total indictable3 KYCP 732 700 699 577 638 575 553 566 511 879 785 Summar y4 KYCQ 182 198 187 163 180 203 194 174 135 296 258 Motor ing5 KYCR 58 57 98 97 82 102 89 94 76 280 230 All offences KYCS 972 955 984 837 900 880 836 834 722 1 455 1 273 1 See chapter text. For the purpose of criminal proceedings, prior to 30 August 2005, a juvenile refers to a person aged 10 years or more but under 17. From 30 August 2005, the youth justice system was extended to include those under the age of 18. The number of juveniles convicted in 2005 and 2006 refers to those aged 10 years or more but under 18. 2 1998 and 1999 figures include ’dangerous driving’. 3 From 2000, includes ’indictable-only’ motoring offences. 4 Excludes motoring offences. 5 Prior to 2000 includes all motoring offences (except for note 2 above). From 2000, includes summary and triable-either-way motor ing offences. Source: Norther n Ireland Office: 028 9052 7157 184 Crime and justice 11.23 Disposals given to those convicted by cour tNor thern Ireland Numbers 1996 1997 1998 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 Magistrates court - all offences Pr ison1 KYAO 1 003 989 996 1 278 1 356 1 048 1 107 1 133 1 101 977 1 018 Custody Probation Order1 EOG9 .. .. .. .. .. .. .. 7 7 9 12 Young offenders centre KYAP 443 430 326 243 191 209 288 395 456 416 366 Tr aining school2 KYAQ 147 148 136 13 .. .. .. .. .. .. .. Juvenile Justice Centre order2 OEUX .. .. .. 22 78 72 58 48 50 50 35 Total immediate custody KYAR 1 593 1 567 1 458 1 556 1 625 1 329 1 453 1 583 1 614 1 452 1 431 Pr ison suspended KYAS 1 722 1 506 1 025 1 080 1 247 1 215 1 278 1 407 1 469 1 584 1 692 YOC suspended KYAT 444 461 139 104 93 77 100 201 372 375 335 Attendance centre KYAU 91 66 55 14 20 37 84 91 108 127 132 Probation/super vision3 KYAV 1 134 1 155 1 473 1 246 1 096 1 070 1 005 974 991 977 1 045 Community service order KYAW 591 561 622 678 726 587 643 623 647 628 597 Combination order OEUZ .. .. 38 7 48 24 36 96 78 106 133 Fine4 KYAX 20 614 21 313 17 956 18 076 17 716 16 439 15 968 17 546 18 520 17 231 17 311 Recognizance KYAY 1 203 1 267 1 134 1 089 1 357 810 912 1 091 913 853 693 Conditional discharge KYAZ 1 679 1 597 1 538 1 439 1 286 1 559 1 497 1 526 1 524 1 326 1 093 Absolute discharge KYBA 509 424 303 223 242 209 163 201 183 148 129 Youth conference order5 GGL8 .. .. .. .. .. .. .. .. 21 74 304 Community responsibility order GGL9 .. .. .. .. .. .. .. .. 1 32 71 Reparation order J8FR .. .. .. .. .. .. .. .. .. .. 1 Other KYBC 15 8 123 221 57 61 104 215 190 122 61 Total KYBD 29 595 29 925 25 864 25 733 25 513 23 417 23 243 25 554 26 631 25 035 25 028 Crown cour t - all offences Pr ison1 KYBE 469 475 520 386 521 407 410 238 259 248 318 Custody Probation Order1 EOH2 .. .. .. .. .. .. .. 331 332 370 416 Young offenders centre KYBF 106 111 63 67 32 42 23 51 47 41 38 Tr aining school2 KYBG − 4 2 − .. .. .. .. .. .. .. Juvenile Justice Centre order2 VQEV .. .. − − − − 2 − − − 1 Total immediate custody KYBH 575 590 585 453 553 449 435 620 638 659 773 Pr ison suspended KYBI 253 220 199 185 313 262 220 240 262 260 267 YOC suspended KYBJ 71 60 49 41 48 37 35 50 72 45 42 Attendance centre KYBK − − − − − − 1 − − − 1 Probation/super vision3 KYBL 49 47 70 43 68 48 49 63 93 79 91 Community service order KYBM 54 37 33 24 29 45 25 27 33 31 32 Combination order ZAEP .. .. 13 6 7 5 18 34 33 40 22 Fine4 KYBN 39 40 25 20 40 38 32 49 108 57 51 Recognizance KYBO 7 10 7 − 4 11 12 8 6 9 8 Conditional discharge KYBR 30 31 23 17 38 36 20 24 45 28 33 Absolute discharge KYBS − 1 6 − 3 − 6 1 1 6 4 Youth conference order5 GGM2 .. .. .. .. .. .. .. .. − − 5 Community responsibility order GGM3 .. .. .. .. .. .. .. .. − − − Reparation order J8FS .. .. .. .. .. .. .. .. .. .. − Other KYBU 3 3 7 2 2 2 4 5 3 6 6 Total KYBV 1 081 1 039 1 017 791 1 105 933 857 1 121 1 294 1 220 1 335 1 Custody Probation Orders cannot be separately identified from ’prison’ sentences from 1998 to 2002. Thus during this timeframe, figures for pr ison include custody probation orders. 2 The Juvenile Justice Centre order replaced the training school order from 31st Januar y 1999. 3 Super vision orders were abolished with the introduction of the Criminal Justice (Children) Norther n Ireland Order 1998. 4 From 2000, fine incorporates ’fine plus disqualification’ and ’fine plus penalty points’. 5 Refers to the number of youth conference orders completed. Source: Norther n Ireland Office: 028 9052 7157 185 Crime and justice 11.24 Prisons and Young Offenders CentresNor thern Ireland Receptions and average population Numbers 1997 1998 1999 2000 2001 2002 2003 2004 2005 2006 2007 Receptions: Reception of untried pr isoners KEOA 2 188 2 284 2 497 2 197 1 922 2 337 2 439 2 440 2 776 3 193 2 929 Reception of sentenced prisoners: Impr isonment under sentence of immediate custody1 KEOB 1 062 949 963 1 001 791 916 1 032 975 966 1 075 1 123 Impr isonment in default of payment of a fine KEOC 1 513 1 530 1 423 1 261 1 090 990 1 143 1 296 1 437 1 569 1 425 Total KEOD 2 575 2 479 2 386 2 262 1 881 1 906 2 175 2 271 2 403 2 644 2 548 Reception into Young Offender Centres: Detention under sentence of immediate custody KEOE 331 347 346 282 252 315 268 287 222 229 247 Detention in default of payment of a fine KEOF 366 385 417 389 303 250 310 351 377 382 299 Total KEOG 697 732 763 671 555 565 578 638 599 611 546 Other receptions2 KEOL 42 70 38 56 58 57 117 106 134 24 38 Daily average population: Unconvicted3 KEON 376 383 377 317 272 347 393 456 450 531 531 Convicted4 KEOP 1 256 1 124 867 751 638 679 767 818 851 902 935 Total KEOM 1 632 1 507 1 244 1 068 910 1 026 1 160 1 274 1 301 1 433 1 466 1 Includes those detained under Section 73 of the Children and Young Per- sons (NI) Act 1968. 2 Non-cr iminal pr isoners including those imprisoned for non-payment of maintenance, non-payment of debt, contempt of court or are being held un- der the terms of an Immigration Act. 3 Prisoners on remand or awaiting trial and prisoners committed by civil process. 4 Includes those sentenced to immediate custody and fine defaulters. Sources: The Norther n Ireland Prison Population in 2007; Nor thern Ireland Office: 028 9052 7534 Crime and Justice Recorded crime statistics Court proceedings and police cautions Expenditure on penal establishments in Scotland work_m5nsaaqscvc2re25tlpp3dhgwq ---- EGALITARIAN JUSTICE AND CHOSEN BRUTE TASTE* Knight, C. (2009) Egalitarian justice and valuational judgment. Journal of Moral Philosophy, 6 (4). pp. 482-498. ISSN 1740-4681 http://eprints.gla.ac.uk/49956/ Deposited on: 22 March 2011 Enlighten – Research publications by members of the University of Glasgow http://eprints.gla.ac.uk http://eprints.gla.ac.uk/view/author/3829.html http://eprints.gla.ac.uk/view/journal_volume/Journal_of_Moral_Philosophy.html http://eprints.gla.ac.uk/view/journal_volume/Journal_of_Moral_Philosophy.html Egalitarian Justice and Valuational Judgment CARL KNIGHT* Adam Smith Research Foundation and Department of Politics University of Glasgow Glasgow, UK Contemporary discussions of egalitarian justice have often focused on the issue of expensive taste. G. A. Cohen has recently abandoned the view that all chosen disadvantages are non-compensable, now maintaining that chosen expensive judgmental tastes – those endorsed by valuational judgment – are compensable as it is unreasonable to expect persons not to develop them. But chosen expensive brute taste – the main type of non-compensable expensive taste on the new scheme – cannot be described in such a way that there is a normative difference between it and chosen expensive judgmental taste. As there are related problems with denying compensation for the other kind of expensive taste that might remain non- compensable, Cohen’s position on taste appears to be either implausible or virtually indistinguishable from that of equality of welfare. However, compensation for valuational judgment-based expensive taste might be justified on grounds of responsibility. Keywords: Choice, G. A. Cohen, Equality, Justice, Responsibility, Expensive Taste. I. Introduction Consider the following scenario: 1. (a) Steve holds £10. (b) Harry holds £10. 2. (a) Steve’s taste is such that he would obtain 1 unit of welfare (hereafter: unit) from consuming a hamburger. (b) Steve’s taste is such that he would obtain 10 units from consuming a steak. (c) Harry’s taste is such that he would obtain 10 units from consuming a hamburger. d) Harry’s taste is such that he would obtain 1 unit from consuming a steak. e) No change in the tastes of Steve or Harry is now possible. 3. (a) A hamburger now costs £2. (b) A steak now costs £10. 4. Steve would now prefer to have Harry’s taste. 5. (a) Prior to t (=a point in the past) Steve’s taste was that of Harry’s. (b) Harry has not deliberately cultivated his taste, nor could he ever have eliminated it. (c) Steve deliberately cultivated his present taste at t. Which of these facts is relevant to egalitarian distributive justice? A wealth egalitarian replies that 1 alone is relevant, and that the existing distribution is perfectly just. A welfare egalitarian begs to differ: on her account, 2 and 3 also come into play. She views the distribution as unjust, on the grounds that Steve is only able to secure 10 units with his funds, whereas Harry is able to secure 50 units with his. Steve has expensive taste, in the sense that he is only able to secure below average welfare with average income. The welfare egalitarian views Steve’s expensive taste as a disadvantage that entitles him to compensation. In his highly influential article, ‘What is Equality?’, Ronald Dworkin criticized the welfare egalitarian’s stance on ‘champagne tastes’ as counterintuitive.[1] His favoured theory of equality of resources did not, however, agree with equality of wealth’s stance that 1 is the only relevant fact. Dworkin suggested that 4 is also relevant, for on his scheme those with dispreferred tastes (or ‘cravings’) are entitled to compensation. Another position was proposed in response to Dworkin in G. A. Cohen’s well-known paper ‘On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice’.[2] Cohen urged that compensation for expensive tastes did not appear counterintuitive where those tastes were unchosen; on the contrary, such compensation was mandated by justice. On this account, which may be referred to as equality of opportunity for welfare,[3] 1, 2, 3 and 5 all appear to be relevant. Cohen has recently modified his account, suggesting that some tastes that are chosen are nevertheless compensable.[4] The present article argues that the position that he now wants to occupy either makes distributive decisions on morally arbitrary grounds or comes close to collapsing into equality of welfare. Nevertheless, he does highlight a possible source of injustice – harsh treatment of valuational judgment-based expensive taste – which the equality debate has thus far overlooked.[5] This points to the need for renewed focus on the relationship between principles of distributive justice and the content of responsibility. The paper starts in earnest in section II, which clarifies Cohen’s position on responsibility. Cohen is now clear that responsibility for possessing one’s taste is not itself important; it is rather responsibility for the expense of one’s taste that matters. Section III introduces Cohen’s new distinction between judgmental and brute taste. Here Cohen’s additional condition for compensation for a taste – that it is based upon valuational judgment – is discussed, and the most plausible interpretation of this condition is put forward. In sections IV and V the difficulty of finding cases in which Cohen may reasonably refuse compensation is demonstrated. This difficulty is due to the fact that, on the two available interpretations of Cohen’s account, the non- compensable expensive taste – chosen brute taste – cannot be formulated in such a way that it is morally distinguishable from (compensable) chosen judgmental taste. In section VI one special type of case in which Cohen might refuse to provide compensation is described, and a familiar kind of problem with such a refusal is identified. This puts Cohen’s view uncomfortably close to equality of welfare. Section VII notes that one might bite the bullet at this point, but only at the cost of facing Dworkin’s expensive tastes objection. It is argued in section VIII that a more promising strategy is to account for valuational judgment by construing it as an obstacle to full responsibility. We need not assume that valuational judgment is such an obstacle, but only that it might be. II. Responsibility and Expense In ‘Expensive Taste Rides Again’, Cohen states that he wishes to revise the following first sentence of the ‘flagship statement’ of his earlier essay: ‘I distinguish among expensive tastes according to whether or not their bearer can reasonably be held responsible for them’.[6] Cohen now says that this sentence (together with similar statements in ‘Currency’) is poorly formulated. A suitable reformulation would replace ‘them’ with ‘the fact that her tastes are expensive’. He adds the following: ‘It is, as I made it abundantly clear elsewhere in “Currency,” precisely that fact for which the question of responsibility is crucial’.[7] Without this clarification the first sentence of the flagship statement is at best ambiguous and at worst morally implausible. The original formulation may be read as suggesting that justice distinguishes between responsibility and lack of responsibility for the existence of tastes that now happen to be expensive. Persons are entitled to compensation if they have what Dworkin calls bad preference luck, ‘which is their bad luck in having the preferences that they do because these preferences are expensive’. [8] On this account, the bare fact that Steve chose to generate his taste (fact 5) disqualifies his claim for compensation. But suppose that Steve’s taste was not expensive when he cultivated his taste, and that he could not have predicted that it would become so in the future. He has been unlucky, not in having the taste that he does, but in that his taste has become expensive. He has an unchosen disadvantage (a taste for an expensive food) which would be overlooked by one concerned only with bad preference luck. This possibility suggests that responsibility for holding the taste does not matter in the absence of responsibility for its expensiveness. For this reason Cohen now makes it clear that it is responsibility for the expensiveness of one’s taste that matters.[9] People are entitled to compensation on this account where they have what Dworkin describes as bad price luck, ‘which is bad luck in the high cost of the preferences they have’.[10] This would be a relevant set of facts on such an account: 6. (a) At t a steak cost £2. (b) At t a hamburger cost £2. (c) Steve could not reasonably have been expected to anticipate the rise in price of steaks from t to the present. Cohen believes that it would be unfair to penalize Steve for the unforeseen economic changes that have replaced the favourable circumstances depicted in 6 with the unfavourable circumstances depicted in 3. No transfer would be due if Steve knew such changes were likely to occur but gambled that they would not, or hoped that they would, maybe because he views expense as itself desirable.[11] But this is not the case here. As it is, Steve suffers from a welfare deficit for which he is not relevantly responsible; such deficits are compensable on Cohen’s scheme, and the first element of the reformulation of his flagship statement reflects that. III. Brute Taste and Judgmental Taste The second sentence of Cohen’s original flagship statement reads thus: There are those [tastes] which he [an individual] could not have helped forming and/or could not now unform, and then there are those for which, by contrast, he can be held responsible, because he could have forestalled them and/or because he could now unlearn them.[12] Cohen believes that the failings of this second sentence are more substantial than those of the first. The problem is not merely that his position is poorly expressed: the position itself is at fault. While Cohen still believes that some chosen tastes are non-compensable, he now maintains that others do give rise to valid claims for compensation. The former category are brute tastes, ‘which do not embody judgments of valuation’.[13] Cohen offers the example of ‘my own liking for Diet Coke, which embodies no particular approval of it’.[14] Judgmental tastes, by contrast, ‘are informed by valuational judgment’. Cohen explains his change of stance as follows: I no longer think that the mere fact that people chose to develop and/or could now school themselves out of an expensive judgmental taste means that they should pick up the tab for it, and that is precisely because they did and do identify with it, and therefore cannot reasonably be expected to have not developed it or to rid themselves of it.[15] The moral idea driving the distributive proposal is that some persons are disadvantaged by their identification with certain tastes which turn out to be expensive, since that identification leads them to develop those tastes. Cohen observes that this takes his position even further away from Dworkin’s: So what Dworkin gives as a reason for withholding compensation – the subjects’ approving identification with their expensive tastes – is something that I regard as a reason for offering it, since, where identification is present, it is, standardly, the agents’ very bad luck that a preference with which they strongly identify happens to be expensive, and to expect them to forego or to restrict satisfaction of that preference (because it is expensive) is, therefore, to ask them to accept an alienation from what is deep in them.[16] Cohen’s move should not exactly be to turn Dworkin on his head. One may recall that Dworkin is interested in the presence or absence of identification with taste right now: hence, on his account, fact 4 in the hamburger-and-steak case mentioned at the outset justifies compensation for Steve (given fact 1). Here Cohen, like Dworkin, focuses on present (dis)identification: unfair disadvantage arises ‘where identification is present’. However, we have seen that elsewhere in the same paper he focuses on the history of identification as well: persons who did identify or who do identify with a taste ‘… cannot reasonably be expected to have not developed it or to rid themselves of it’. In other words, present (dis)identification matters for establishing whether it is reasonable to expect an expensive taste to be unlearned, while past (dis)identification matters for the key issue of establishing whether it is reasonable to hold someone accountable for their choice to develop a taste. So why should Cohen maintain that history of identification matters? An answer becomes clear when we consider the case of someone who initially had no identification with an expensive taste, but nevertheless developed it, and subsequently came to identify with it. Cohen has no reason for thinking that it would be unreasonable to ask such a person to bear the cost of their taste whether they can now be rid of it or not, for that cost has arisen directly from a choice that she was not predisposed to make. It is a history of identification that excuses an individual from bearing the cost of their expensive taste; present identification only tells us that an individual who has been so excused cannot be expected to dispose of their taste. IV. Chosen Expensive Brute Taste The discussion of the previous section indicates that the following would be an example of an additional relevant fact on Cohen’s scheme: 7. Prior to and at t, Steve disidentified with the taste he then had and identified with the taste he now has. This embodies my stipulation, given as an interpretation of Cohen, that the (dis)identification must not come after the possession of the taste – it must be what we might call pre(dis)identification. According to Cohen, the presence of this fact diminishes Steve’s liability for his present expensive taste. It shows that, even if Steve is responsible for the fact that the taste he holds is expensive, it would be unreasonable to make him bear its cost.[17] The implications of this revised account are no simple matter. To see them one must first try and establish what exactly a chosen expensive brute taste might look like. This is because they are (with one important exception to be mentioned in section VI) the only kind of expensive taste that Cohen now refuses to provide compensation for, and as such they appear to be the only source of disagreement between Cohen and equality of welfare. I will maintain that, from what little Cohen says about chosen brute taste, it is not clear that they can exist in a form that is differentiated from chosen judgmental taste by any morally significant characteristic. On one of the two available interpretations, Cohen’s account amounts to no more or less than equality of welfare,[18] insofar as it is concerned with welfare;[19] on the other, it amounts to something with (even) less justification. The feature that makes a taste brute in Cohen’s sense is that it ‘does not embody judgments of valuation’. For reasons that should be obvious from the earlier discussion, the kind of judgments of valuation that they do not embody are those that are temporally prior to the taste itself. Steve’s taste for steak does not go from being judgmental to being brute simply because he stops identifying with it some time after he has acquired it, for Cohen’s question of whether Steve could reasonably have been expected to turn down the opportunity to cultivate that taste, given the cost that would impose upon him, can obviously only apply before taste acquisition. The kind of taste we are looking for is one that is chosen and initially not supported by value judgments. How might the origins of Cohen’s own taste for Diet Coke meet both of these criteria? Were Jerry (as I will call this character) brought up to have this taste or hypnotized into having it, it would fail to meet the criterion of being chosen.[20] This would also be the case if his first sip had him hooked, and that sip resulted from, say, a bartending error or lack of alternative beverages. Contrariwise, if Jerry made a deliberate attempt to cultivate that taste it would fail to meet the non-judgmental criterion. That attempt must be based on some kind of value judgment, however sensible or fatuous it may be, for otherwise his behaviour is inexplicable. There are further possibilities that may appear to salvage chosen brute taste. First, suppose that Jerry makes no deliberate attempt to cultivate a taste for Diet Coke and has no preidentification with it, but that he tries it anyway. Perhaps he just wants to see what it tastes like. Or maybe he has decided to live his life as a ‘free spirit’, which right now means trying some Diet Coke for no particular reason. Either way, Jerry’s first sip results in taste formation. For the moment, let us grant that the taste that is formed in a case like this is brute. Although preidentification with taste is absent, other kinds of relevant value judgments are present. It seems to me that Jerry could only have not taken his sip by acting in a fashion that contradicted his value judgment that he ought to find out what Diet Coke tastes like, or that he ought to drink it just because that’s what he wants to do. Such contradiction is not directly related to taste. It is, however, obviously an incident of self-infliction of cost. Were it identical in every regard except the structure of its relation to taste, Cohen would say that it could not reasonably be expected of Jerry. If this kind of self-infliction is unreasonable where the judgment endorses the taste I do not see any reason why it is less unreasonable where the judgment endorses something else that can only be realized by performing an action that may or will result in taste formation. There is a slight causal difference but no moral difference: in both types of case we require individuals ‘to accept an alienation from what is deep in them’ if they are not to suffer a welfare deficit. On this natural reading of Cohen, he appears to base compensation on a morally arbitrary distinction. V. An Alternative Interpretation Suppose, then, that we take a more liberal reading. Here we describe a taste such as Jerry’s – one that is not preidentified with, but that could only have been avoided at the cost of violating otherwise independent value judgments – as an indirect judgmental taste. The resulting broad sense of judgmental taste, encompassing both indirect judgmental taste and direct judgmental taste (instances of which are preidentified with), is somewhat strained as a construal of Cohen, given that it includes ‘taste that does not track a judgment of the value of its object’.[21] But it – and the corresponding narrow construal of brute taste – sits far more comfortably with Cohen’s moral argument that it is unreasonable to expect persons to contradict their value judgments. In this case it looks like there is nothing morally arbitrary about compensating for chosen judgmental taste but not for chosen brute taste. But the revised position also radically limits the occurrence of chosen brute taste (that is, a chosen taste that could have been avoided at no self-inflicted cost). Usually a taste must be either unchosen or endorsed, somewhere along the line, by valuational judgment; in the odd case where it is both unendorsed and, in some sense, chosen, compensation is still appropriate. This is shown in two more kinds of cases. We might suppose that Jerry has no preidentification with Diet Coke but that he is a ‘diceman’ – one who makes his choices in a random fashion – and, when ordering his drinks, Diet Coke’s number comes up. Or we might suppose that, while Jerry’s action might look like it could be explained as either experimental or wilfully random, he is simply acting on impulse. In each case we again suppose that the first sip results in taste formation. When presented with cases like Diceman Jerry it is tempting to think that chosen narrow brute taste might ride in on the back of uncertainty about outcomes. The unexpected results of random but deliberate action may appear to be chosen without there having been any question of identification. It is therefore important to note that the actual likelihood of the taste arising from the action, and the individual’s perception of this likelihood, are quite irrelevant to the question of whether the taste is (indirectly) judgmental. All that matters is that the individual could not have performed otherwise without contradicting his own judgment. Even if the individual thought there was no possibility of taste formation, and it was in fact a million to one shot, that taste would be fully judgmental on account of the clear causal link between it, the action, and the endorsement of the action. Both this point and the more general point about the infrequency with which chosen narrow brute taste can occur is illustrated well in the Diceman Jerry case. Diceman Jerry’s taste is, I will allow, chosen and not itself preidentified with. But the endorsement of running one’s life on the roll of a dice is clearly a value judgment. That preidentification with randomizing is, in this instance, bound up with the taste. Even though the link between Diceman Jerry’s taste and his judgment is indirect and fortuitous, his taste is judgmental, for he could have declined the option of drinking Diet Coke only by alienating himself from his own judgment. This causal relationship is all that is required to show that the taste is not brute in the narrow sense. The final, impulsive case faces the initial worry that no taste formed in this way could be chosen. But I am willing to grant, for the sake of argument, that choice may be present here. This issue aside, impulsive action appears to present the best opportunity for non-compensable chosen brute taste to arise. Even so, Jerry’s behaviour is presumably explainable in one of two ways, and neither of these will do. Firstly, there may be a value judgment even further back in the causal chain than in the earlier two cases. This judgment may direct Jerry to act spontaneously and without regard to consequences. This case is not relevantly different from that of the self-defined free spirit. As before, the taste can be treated as non-compensable only if we demand that Jerry alienate himself from his judgment. On the alternative reading of Cohen, the taste is, again, not brute. Secondly, and more interestingly, Jerry may be following no value judgment whatsoever. He may by nature be an extremely impetuous person. It may have never crossed his mind that acting in a more considered way is a viable option. This is the one kind of case where the more liberal reading of Cohen can, like the more straightforward construal, identify chosen brute (i.e. unendorsed) taste. But the common denial of compensation in both instances is morally arbitrary. If it is unreasonable to expect someone to act against their valuational judgment, it is, if anything, more unreasonable to expect someone to act against their natural temperament, where no reasons for such behavioural modification have even been entertained. The complete absence of valuational judgment makes it inappropriate to punish (or reward) in this case as one might were a full moral agent involved. Even if we allow that there is choice, there is not responsibility.[22] VI. Costlessly Removable Expensive Taste The basic problem we have so far encountered is that one can generally choose to undergo a course of action that may inadvertently result in the acquisition of a taste only where one holds value judgments that recommend that course of action. A taste of this kind is an indirect judgmental taste. One can only avoid this conclusion by failing to acknowledge the cost involved in acting contrary to value judgments that are only indirectly linked to the acquisition of the taste (for example, ones recommending ‘taste testing’ or spontaneity). This is precisely what Cohen does on the more natural reading mentioned above. But I can see no moral justification for such a position. Indeed, it seems to run counter to the unreasonableness-of-expecting-self-imposed-costs justification that Cohen attempts to support his stance with. If, on the other hand, we work with the more liberally interpreted senses of brute and judgmental taste, chosen brute taste can only be held by the very impulsive. So interpreted, Cohen’s position is either, again, morally arbitrary (if we penalize purely impulsive behaviour) or virtually normatively identical with equality of welfare. In the latter case, it makes conceptual distinctions (between brute and judgmental taste, and between chosen and unchosen taste) that equality of welfare does not, but the only normatively relevant combination is all but impossible since non-purely impulsive chosen brute tastes are reclassified as indirect judgmental tastes. I say ‘all but impossible’ as there is one special case where it may appear that Cohen could still reasonably deny compensation for expensive taste. This is the case of costlessly removable expensive taste. Whether it was initially chosen or not, Cohen denies compensation for expensive tastes that can be removed at no expense – which is to say not only that the tastes are not presently identified with, but also that there are no ‘incidental’ costs that are unrelated to identification. Equality of welfare would even compensate in the case where an individual with such a taste obstinately refused to remove it. The absence of present identification marks these tastes as brute in the sense that was rejected in section III above. The absence of incidental costs is much the more demanding of the two requirements mentioned in the previous paragraph. Even where a taste is disidentified with, there will almost always be some financial expenditure, lost time or other inconvenience involved in schooling oneself out of it that results in a welfare loss. As costlessly removable expensive tastes are little more than a possibility, the space between the broad judgmental taste view and equality of welfare is barely a sliver. Yet the rarity of costlessly removable expensive tastes is not the most substantial bar to their serving as an effective prop for Cohen’s position. The refusal to compensate for these tastes is morally suspect for reasons that are very much parallel to those that applied to the natural reading of Cohen (where judgmental taste was narrowly construed). A deliberate failure to remove a taste, even where there is no cost involved, presumably itself involves valuational judgment. We might again ask why it is unreasonable to ask people to act against their value judgments in some cases, but not in others. Someone endorsing compensation for judgmental taste in either the narrow sense (admitting direct judgmental tastes only) or broad sense (admitting both direct and indirect judgmental tastes) faces an unpalatable choice. They could treat the value judgments that oppose costless removal of expensive tastes as the basis for compensation for those tastes (either because the judgments are necessarily tied up with judgmental taste or for independent reasons). Or they could refuse compensation, in which case their moral consistency is in doubt, given the original justification for compensation for expensive judgmental tastes. VII. Biting the Bullet The argument that expensive judgmental taste should not be penalized has some intuitive support. But consistent endorsement of what appears to be its key premise – that it is wrong to penalize persons for choices that are required by their valuational judgment – commits Cohen to more than he acknowledges. For the premise to be consistently endorsed, both the broad construal of judgmental taste and compensation for costlessly removable expensive tastes that are not removed is required. This treatment of tastes is identical to that of equality of welfare, even if the justification is different.[23] It appears that Cohen is still determined to put distance between his account and equality of welfare.[24] If the arguments presented above have helped to clarify the size of that distance and, in particular, the normative difficulties that are involved in retaining it, they would for those reasons alone have some significance. But what if Cohen, or someone endorsing similar premises, were to bite the bullet, and accept that something very close to equality of welfare is the correct account of egalitarian justice after all? This move faces the arguments against equality of welfare presented by Dworkin, which could be applied to the new position with minimal revision. The objection to social allowance for expensive tastes is of course foremost amongst these. One question, then, is whether Cohen’s focus on the (alleged) wrongness of penalizing acts required by valuational judgment suggests a new way around the objection. It seems quite clear that it does not. In Dworkin’s original presentation, ‘someone (Louis) sets out deliberately to cultivate some taste or ambition he does not now have’, for the specific purpose of ‘trying to make his life a better life in some way’.[25] So it seems reasonable to assume that, from the outset, Louis is characterized as acting on valuational judgment. But Dworkin thinks that of no help to his cause: This does not make his claim for extra resources any more appealing or less counter- intuitive … . On the contrary, the fact that he is acting so deliberately in his own interests seems to make his claim, if anything, less appealing than the claim of someone who tries an expensive experience on a whim, for the pleasure of the moment, and then finds that he is hooked.[26] Whether one agrees with Dworkin’s position or not is unlikely to be affected by Cohen’s change of emphasis. As Cohen acknowledges, Dworkin always accounted for valuational judgment – he just did not think it mattered. Takers of the bullet-biting strategy are squarely in Dworkin’s sights. VIII. Valuational Judgment as Responsibility-Diminishing It seems to me that there may be a less hazardous way of endorsing the premise that it is wrong for persons to be disadvantaged by valuational judgment-endorsed acts. On one prominent construal of equality of opportunity for welfare, which Cohen has consistently endorsed, a disadvantage such as an expensive taste is non-compensable only where the holder has genuinely chosen it – that is, where she is responsible for it in a deep, metaphysically valid way. The appropriate distribution is dependent on both which account of free will and determinism is correct and facts particular to each case.[27] The presence or absence of preidentification, or of other, less direct value judgments that have resulted in taste formation (such as those of Dicemen), are candidates for relevant particular facts. It might be thought that, although a history of valuational judgment is not grounds for assuming full non-responsibility, it may diminish an individual’s responsibility for developing their taste. As the strength of the value judgments – and the degrees of difficulty and pain involved in acting contrary to them – increase, so responsibility decreases. We might, then, hold that Cohen’s discomfort with the position he took in ‘Currency’ is based on a failure to appreciate the full range of considerations that responsibility may take into account. The complaint is really with certain prevalent conceptions of responsibility and related concepts, such as choice, which fail to recognize the significant role of valuational judgment. That a person is acting on valuational judgment is not typically taken to be a factor in favour of their case for compensation – Dworkin for one thinks quite the opposite. Once the argument shifts to this level there appears to be little problem with the position Cohen took in ‘Currency’. One gets the outcome of compensating for valuational judgment-based tastes by combining conventional equality of opportunity for welfare with a particular account of responsibility. Now it might be asked why this strategy should be preferred to the bullet-biting one. The answer is twofold. First is the way it accounts for the moral significance of variations in the ease with which preidentification and other relevant judgments can be contradicted. In some cases, an individual may only act against their valuational judgment at cost of considerable self- contradiction, but in others, while there is some cost involved, it is relatively minor. An agent who acts against their preidentification with an expensive taste for the theatre might consequently experience great inner-anguish or hardly anything at all – it just depends on the character of the preidentification. In light of this, the strategy suggested by the alternative reading of Cohen, under which full compensation is to be provided in each case of valuational judgment-based taste, is insufficiently discriminating. A possible retort here is this: why not just adopt a further interpretation – or really, by this point, reinterpretation – of Cohen, such that his position admits of degrees. The more promising version of this approach works with the alternative reading of Cohen’s position, avoiding the moral arbitrariness of the natural interpretation, but placing all tastes somewhere on a continuum of valuational judgment strength. On other words, we accept that all tastes are judgmental (broad sense), but hold that those tastes whose cultivation could only have been avoided at great personal cost give entitlements to higher levels of compensation than those whose cultivation could have been avoided at a smaller price. This is certainly not the position that Cohen takes, and not only because it relies on the alternative reading of Cohen. For Cohen also does not seem to consider the possibility of morally relevant variations in the strength of identification; indeed, his discussion of (direct) judgmental taste seems just to assume that there is strong identification. But it does at least retain Cohen’s identification of valuational judgment and non-responsibility as two distinct grounds for compensation. There is, however, an additional argument for a subsumption of the first of these grounds under the second which points to a weakness common to both the bullet-biting strategy and the ‘sliding scale’ view of broad judgmental tastes. The argument is that both positions give hostages to fortune, in the sense that (direct or indirect) taste-creating value judgments are specified as grounds for compensation, be it full or partial, regardless of which account of responsibility happens to be correct. I do not see any reason for thinking that, whatever expensive taste- excusing properties valuational judgment has, they are independent of responsibility. If we take the most straightforward case, that of direct judgmental taste, I submit that the appropriate response to a particular instance of preidentification is very likely to depend on questions such as these: What is the causal history of the preidentification? Was the agent aware of the costs of acting as suggested by the preidentification? How do other agents with similar levels of preidentification and information act? Which general account of free will and determinism is correct? On this account, can acts based on preidentification be genuinely voluntary, or not? Does this account, combined with an account of egalitarian justice, allow that some acts based on preidentification are compensable? If so, which acts, and how much compensation? These are questions of responsibility. I do not see how we can detach the moral significance of taste-creating value judgments from them, far less assume an overwhelming moral significance however we answer them. IX. Concluding Remarks The argument of this article suggests that egalitarians looking to occupy a position on expensive taste that falls between conventional equality of opportunity for welfare and equality of welfare cannot expect the brute taste/judgmental taste distinction to carry the justificatory load. Nevertheless, the distinction serves a valuable role, in highlighting the possibility that egalitarian justice, especially as depicted by Dworkin, treats the bearers of valuational judgment-based expensive tastes in unduly harsh fashion. I hope to have shown that the corrective to this state of affairs need not be at the level of distributive principle, as Cohen proposes, since the role of valuational judgment in taste formation might be accounted for by the account of responsibility that is utilized by distributive principles. This underlines the importance for political philosophy of the contents of what Susan Hurley calls the ‘black box of responsibility’.[28] The problems with the notion of compensating for valuational judgment-based acts reinforces Hurley’s general contention that different accounts of responsibility have differing implications for accounts of distributive justice. If, as is fairly likely, valuational judgment bears on responsibility, and takes much (if not all) of its moral significance from that connection, it is a mistake to decide on its weight in distributive decisions quite independently of responsibility considerations. Interestingly, this is one case where a ‘luck egalitarian’ – or more specifically, ‘thin luck egalitarian’[29] – position may actually be reinforced by filling in the details of responsibility, since the non-luck egalitarian addition (compensation for judgmental taste) to a luck egalitarian position (equality of opportunity for welfare) may thereby be shown to be otiose. It might be objected that the conventional-equality-of-opportunity-for-welfare- plus-valuational-judgment-sensitive-account-of-responsibility strategy defended in the preceding two sections gives a hostage to fortune which, while different from that of the Cohenian alternatives, is no less problematic. This is its commitment that valuational judgment is necessarily a condition – or even, on the strongest version of the view, the sole condition – for non- responsibility. The objection is sound. Even so, to me this seems like the most plausible way of ensuring compensation for expensive taste-creating value judgments, for reasons already mentioned. Since I am unconvinced that such compensation is demanded by justice (although it may well be) I would prefer to leave the question of exactly what responsibility is as open as possible. Of course, in doing this, I face the further objection that I am myself trying to keep the lid on the black box of responsibility. In reply, I would point out that there seems to be no structural deficiency or superfluity with the thin luck egalitarian position that, like special compensation for valuational judgment-based expensive taste, would be exposed as such once a full account of responsibility was provided. It is quite compatible with responsibility, whatever role the latter gives to valuational judgment. I am not so much keeping the lid on the black box of responsibility as refusing to prejudge its contents. The strategy I propose replies to the Dworkinian expensive taste objection in just the way that Cohen intended in ‘Currency’, arguing that, regardless of whether an expensive taste is presently identified with, compensation seems reasonable where the holder is not responsible for the expense of her taste. We allow for the possibility that a history of valuational judgment is responsibility-diminishing, but we do not insist that it is a responsibility-diminishing factor, irrespective of what else there is to know about responsibility, nor (as the bullet-biting and sliding scale Cohen-derived positions suggest) that it is a compensation-entitling factor, irrespective of whether it diminishes responsibility. This is the right tack to take in the absence of overwhelmingly strong arguments for the distributive significance of valuational judgment. ------------------------------------ * I would like to thank Richard Arneson, Hillel Steiner, Andrew Williams, and an anonymous referee for their helpful comments. Research for this article was supported by the Arts and Humanities Research Council and the Worldwide Universities Network. [1] Ronald Dworkin, ‘What is Equality? Part Two: Equality of Resources’, Philosophy and Public Affairs 10 (1981), pp. 283-345. Reprinted as chapters 1 and 2 of Ronald Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2000). [2] G. A. Cohen, ‘On the Currency of Egalitarian Justice’, Ethics 99 (1989), pp. 906-44. See also Richard J. Arneson, ‘Equality and Equal Opportunity for Welfare’, Philosophical Studies 56 (1989), pp. 77-93. John Roemer, Theories of Distributive Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1996). [3] Cohen actually endorsed equal access to advantage, where advantage included both welfare and resources (‘Currency’, pp. 907, 916-21). I will set this difference aside, as Cohen allows (G. A. Cohen, ‘Expensive Taste Rides Again’, in Justine Burley (ed.), Dworkin and His Critics (Oxford: Blackwell, 2004), p. 4. (Cohen believes that ‘access’ and ‘opportunity’ are different concepts, but I can detect no difference between them on Arneson’s definition of the latter [see Arneson, ‘Equal opportunity for welfare’, pp. 85-6].) [4] Cohen, ‘Expensive Taste Rides Again’. [5] For an accessible account of the debate up to Cohen’s latest contribution see Jonathan Wolff, ‘Equality: The Recent History of an Idea’, Journal of Moral Philosophy 4 (2007), pp. 125-36. [6] Cohen, ‘Currency’, p. 923; cf. p. 920. [7] Cohen, ‘Expensive Taste Rides Again’, p. 7. [8] Ronald Dworkin, ‘Replies’, in Justine Burley (ed.), Dworkin and His Critics, p. 344. [9] This is also suggested on p. 927 of ‘Currency’. But note that Cohen introduces this thought as one of a number of additional comments on Dworkin’s position that come after his main argument against it. Despite Cohen’s protestations, it is far from ‘abundantly clear’ that his main concern was always with expensiveness of taste rather than taste itself, and the only textual support he offers is the passage cited above. [10] Dworkin, ‘Replies’, p. 344. [11] See Cohen, ‘Expensive Taste Rides Again’, pp. 12, 14. [12] Cohen, ‘Currency’, p. 923. [13] Cohen, ‘Expensive Taste Rides Again’, p. 7. [14] Cohen, ‘Expensive Taste Rides Again’, p. 7. [15] Cohen, ‘Expensive Taste Rides Again’, p. 7, original emphasis. See also Terry Price, ‘Egalitarian Justice, Luck, and the Costs of Chosen Ends’, American Philosophical Quarterly 36 (1999), pp. 267-78. [16] Cohen, ‘Expensive Taste Rides Again’, p. 7, original emphasis. A note makes it clear that by ‘standardly’ Cohen means only ‘barring the special case where people welcome the fact that their taste is expensive’ (‘Expensive Taste Rides Again’, p. 27 n. 13, original emphasis). [17] Cohen strongly hints that those who develop expensive tastes for snobbish reasons or who unsuccessfully gamble that they will be able to afford them should be denied compensation (‘Expensive Taste Rides Again’, pp. 12, 14, 20-1). But given that such tastes are patently based on valuational judgment, and that Cohen mentions no reasons for denying compensation in these cases of judgmental taste but not others, I find this puzzling, as does Dworkin (Dworkin, ‘Replies’, p. 347). [18] Dworkin said something similar about the position Cohen took in ‘Currency’: ‘that supposedly different ideal (equality of opportunity for welfare) turns out to be equality of welfare under a different name’ (Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue, p. 286). This conclusion is based upon the thought that all tastes are unchosen (and therefore compensable on Cohen’s scheme) as they are themselves the result of uncultivated second-order tastes; see Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue, ch. 7; ‘Replies’, pp. 346-7, 391 n. 22. My conclusion, by contrast, is based on the argument that, on one understanding of Cohen, some tastes can be chosen, but that all such tastes are nevertheless compensable for reasons of valuational judgment. [19] See note 3 above. [20] See Cohen, ‘Expensive Taste Rides Again’, p. 21. [21] Cohen, ‘Expensive Taste Rides Again, p. 8. [22] See sections VIII and XI below. [23] Cohen holds that, even if all expensive tastes were unchosen in the way Dworkin suggests (see note 18 above), and therefore compensable according to equality of opportunity for welfare, there would still remain a difference of principle between that account and equality of welfare; see ‘Expensive Taste Rides Again’, pp. 19-20. It is worth noting that the present situation is very different from this, since Cohen has given a reason for providing compensation for expensive tastes even if they are chosen. [24] Cohen, ‘Expensive Taste Rides Again’, pp. 19-21. [25] Dworkin, ‘What is Equality?’, pp. 229, 230. [26] Dworkin, ‘What is Equality?’, p. 230. [27] Cohen, ‘Expensive Taste Rides Again’, p. 22; Cohen, ‘Equality of What? On Welfare, Goods and Capabilities’, in Martha Nussbaum and Amartya Sen (eds.), The Quality of Life (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993), p. 28. See also Arneson, ‘Equal Opportunity for Welfare’, p. 86; Carl Knight, ‘The Metaphysical Case for Luck Egalitarianism’, Social Theory and Practice 32 (2006), pp. 173-89. [28] See S. L. Hurley, Justice, Luck, and Knowledge (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2003). [29] ‘Thin luck’ is just the opposite correlate of responsibility; see Hurley, Justice, Luck, and Knowledge, ch. 4. citation_temp.pdf http://eprints.gla.ac.uk/49956/ work_mbzil3xkobb5fnhh5sdv3lppye ---- No Job Name Justice and Solidarity: The Contractarian Case against Global Justice David Heyd The Problem: Bootstrapping Charity begins at home, they say. But of course this does not mean that it ends there. It can and should extend way beyond home. The same might be said of respect for persons and their human rights. However, as I wish to argue in this article, justice begins at home and ends there. Or to put it in more theoretical terms, some fundamental forms of justice, particularly distributive justice, are essentially domestic. If that proposition is correct, some recent attempts to estab- lish principles of global justice are conceptually misguided. Theories of justice in the past have been relatively mute as to the identity and the scope of the groups to which the principles of justice apply. The subject groups were often simply presupposed as given. Take classical Greek principles of justice: they were typically meant to regulate the life of the citizens of the polis, a well-defined group of people, consisting mainly of adult, free, Greek males. Minors, slaves, “barbarians” and women were thus left out, beyond the reach of the benefits (and sometimes the burdens) of “just treatment.” All in all, there was hardly any attempt to theoretically justify the boundaries of the relevant group within which justice held sway. The urge to extrapolate the idea of justice to the international sphere is, as its intergenerational analogue, a modern phenomenon (with the possible exception of Christian theology). Both attempts are associated with historical developments regarding the unprecedented control human beings have gained over the welfare of other people living far away, either in location or in time. Like birth control and environmental policies, which enable us to deeply affect the lives of future generations, mass movements of people, money, and ideas in our age of “global- ization” make us much more responsible than ever in the past for the conditions of people on the other side of the globe. However, such attempts at global and intergenerational extensions of justice face serious theoretical obstacles. In this article, I shall leave aside justice to future generations1 and focus on the international parallel, which has also received much attention, particularly since Kant’s On Perpetual Peace. And I will do so from a contractarian approach, since individualism as a metaphysical assumption and the centrality of the will as a normative basis for political legitimation have become trademarks of liberalism and democracy. JOURNAL of SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY, Vol. 38 No. 1, Spring 2007, 112–130. © 2007 Blackwell Publishing, Inc. The problem is strikingly simple: Who takes part in the contract that serves as the basis for either the legitimation of the state’s authority or the justification of the principles of justice? Locke’s answer is that when any number of Men have, by the consent of every individual, made a Community, they have thereby made that Community one Body, with a Power to Act as one Body, which is only by the will and determination of the majority.2 Hobbes’s answer is similar to Locke’s: A Common-wealth is said to be Instituted, when a Multitude of men do Agree, and Covenant, every one, with every one, that to whatsoever Man, or Assembly of Men, shall be given by the major part, the Right to Present the Person of them all . . .3 Locke and Hobbes show how an indeterminate number of people can, through the very act of a covenant, become a cohesive group, referred to as “community” by Locke and “commonwealth” by Hobbes. The cohesion of the newly created group (as against the diffuse nature of “the multitude”) is expressed by the idea of the “body politick” in Locke and that of the one person representing all others in Hobbes. But both philosophers are completely silent about the process through which the individuals join each other to form that covenant. Is there any basis for the grouping of “any number of people” or “a multitude of men”? In other words, why should an individual (in the state of nature, or in any other imaginary original position) join forces to create a political community with these individuals rather than those? Even if the contract has the power to transform “a multitude of men” into a political community, what makes this multitude convene and make an agreement in the first place? Hobbes and Locke would surely respond that the question misses the purpose of the method of the social contract. Individual human beings have never actually lived outside a social community and hence the question of their choice to assemble in this or that way has never arisen. That is to say, individuals are usually born into human societies rather than choose to form or join them. The whole point of the thought-experiment of the social contract is justificatory, namely, to normatively ground the authority of the state retrospectively, or to offer a “post factum” test for its legitimacy and the justice of its institutions. We may guess that for Hobbes and Locke, England was the framework of the social contract as imagined by Englishmen, as was Geneva or France for Rousseau. As long as political communities were fairly homogeneous and relatively separated from each other, the issue of the scope of membership in the social contract could be left unaccounted for or assumed as given. Thus, despite the search for peace and security, believed by Hobbes to be the prime motivating force for the contract, the distinction between the national and international levels of political relations attests to Hobbes’s view that the contract is ultimately “local” in essence. Only in the “national” context is a contract possible; the international resembles the state Justice and Solidarity 113 of nature. But circumstances have changed since the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries and today’s world is characterized by much more heterogeneity in political communities and by a growing interdependence of countries and states. The issues of the identity and number of the parties to the social contract can no longer be brushed aside.4 But the new awareness of the problem of the scope of the contract leaves us in a logical quandary. If the state’s legitimacy (Hobbes and Locke) and the justification of the principles of justice (Rawls) are decided exclusively by a hypothetical contract and if the scope of the group within which this contract is formed cannot be simply taken for granted as given, it seems that the scope of the group must itself be decided by a contract. But the contours of the group engaged in a contract cannot be fixed by the contract itself. The fairness of inclusion or exclusion from the group of contracting parties cannot be determined by the contract, since it must precede it. This is merely a generalization of the well- known problems of real-life political decisions, like universal suffrage or seces- sion. Who should have taken part in the decision in England in 1918 whether women should get the vote—men only, or men and women? Or, who should vote on the proposal that Quebec secede from the Canadian federation—the Quebecois alone, or the whole Canadian electorate?5 Consider the two radical solutions to the question about the scope of the group of participants in the social contract: everyone or, alternatively, just one. Both are attempts to provide a universal basis to the contract, thus avoiding the pitfalls of controversial contingent restrictions on its range of application. However, if we say that everyone is a party to the contract, who exactly is included? All human beings in the world? Adults only? Are future people to be included in the group of “everyone”? Actual future people, or also possible future people? Should the group include also non-human rational beings as in Kant’s Kingdom of Ends? Clearly, these are substantive philosophical questions relating to the proper reference of “everyone” and they must be settled on a non- contractarian basis. Universal suffrage is a noble ideal, but universality itself is always contextual, relating to persons (or entities) of a certain kind. And this “kind” must be specified prior to the contract. The alternative of taking each (one) person, singly, as the proper scope of the method of legitimation by consent is an interesting idea, which was proposed by Rawls himself. The argument is well known: if we admit into the original position people who are all equally rational, mutually disinterested, free and under a veil of ignorance, the imaginary game of a contract among different people becomes superfluous, since all that is required is an individual’s acceptance of a set of principles of justice for society. There is no need for negotiation between identical individuals and hence there remains no point in a contract. However, the Rawlsian introduction of the veil of ignorance shifts the methodology of justification from the principle of consent to the principle of impartiality, deviating from the tradition of the social contract. It thus obviates the issue of the scope of the relevant group within which the principles of justice (or the legitimacy of sovereign power) apply.6 114 David Heyd I suggest that we return to the original idea of a contract between individuals—more than one but less than everyone. My argument is that even if fairness demands that the principles of justice be agreed upon under a veil of ignorance, we must assume an independent motive for people to enter the contract with those particular people rather than with others, a motive that cannot be hidden by that veil. Note that the existence of such a motive belongs to the conditions or circumstances of justice, not to the justification of the principles of justice. The motive only describes the formal requirement for the applicability of the proce- dure of justifying the normative principles. I therefore suggest that we reverse Locke’s and Hobbes’s view: consent does not create a community; it arises out of a sense of community. In American language, “We the people” cannot be defined by the Constitution, since it is this body of people that creates it. Justice: A Matter of Truth or Consent? Before further examining the problem of global justice, we should emphasize that it arises only within a contractarian point of view. Non-contractarian theories of justice have a long and venerable tradition. The fundamental issue separating the two approaches is whether justice is a matter of truth or a matter of consent; is it a property of the world or a human construction; or, whether it is “given” or a product of the will. The first, realist view of justice takes it as characterizing natural or metaphysical harmony, balance or order. It is associated with concepts such as desert, status, role, or proper functioning, and is accordingly grounded in specific descriptions of human essential nature as well as in social or normative ideals. The second, voluntaristic view of justice arises out of skepticism regarding the metaphysical assumptions about human nature and offers in their place a procedural account of justice as the product of the exercise of individual human will in concert with other individual wills under particular constraints (the ideal- ized conditions of the “state of nature,” or the fairness of the constructed “original position”). Some forms of modern liberalism, being aligned with metaphysical skepti- cism, are naturally biased toward a consent-based analysis of justice. Thus, in Hobbes’s theory, there is no application of the concept of justice in the state of nature. It is only after the sovereign is instituted that by his will justice is created. For Locke, even though moral norms exist in the state of nature, justice, in the sense of the actual distribution of property rights, is the outcome of contractual consent. And of course for Rawls, justice is not given in any metaphysical or realistic way, but is a matter for construction, that is, constitution through human cooperative agreement. Pre-Socratic philosophers treated justice as a matter of natural, cosmic harmony. Plato understood justice in terms of a grand scheme of proper function- ing and an ideal system of a division of labor, reflecting the essential nature of human beings and the realization of their potential. Contract-based liberalism, however, treats justice as a matter of social cooperation, that is to say, a voluntary Justice and Solidarity 115 form of interpersonal enterprise. Justice is no more a given truth or principle, but a product of a negotiated deal. But of course, the characterization of the conditions of such negotiation, the so-called “circumstances of justice,” is crucial for exam- ining the possibility of extending justice to the global sphere. Since Hume, the list of the circumstances of justice has included moderate scarcity, limited sympathy, mutual vulnerability or interdependence, and rough equality. We cannot cooperate when extreme scarcity leads us into a life-and- death struggle; we do not have to cooperate when there is unlimited affluence of resources; we cooperate without having to create principles for cooperation when altruism and love serve as sufficient motives; we have reason to cooperate only when we are not self-sufficient but rather depend on each other, either to avoid harm or to create benefits; and if, as in sharply hierarchical societies, we are not more or less equal, our interpersonal behavior will be based on domi- nation rather than cooperation. These circumstances of justice are determined partly by universal human conditions and partly by historical factors. Accord- ingly, the issue of global justice must be considered in the light of both the universal and historically determined factors that make social cooperation pos- sible and valuable. There seems to be no reason to believe that, at least in principle, the circum- stances of justice apply any less to the world as a whole than to domestic societies. There are indeed differences of degree in scarcity and equality on these two respective levels, and there is some debate on the extent of mutual vulnerability and interdependence on the global sphere. However, my concern is with the parameter of limited sympathy. Limited sympathy has been traditionally inter- preted, from Hume to Rawls, in negative terms, namely, as self-interest, or at least as the mutual disinterest of the parties to the contract-based principles of just cooperation. But social contract theorists have neglected the corresponding posi- tive meaning of the idea of limited sympathy, namely, the degree of actual care for others which I would like to argue constitutes a necessary condition for the operation of justice and should be understood as one of the constitutive circum- stances of justice. The idea is the following. The principles of just distribution of a social cake are analytically connected with the conditions of cooperation which enable the production of the cake (on the assumption that such cakes cannot be made by a single individual). But the cooperation to bake a cake is not simply given, since the crucial question is with whom do we want to do the baking and the eating of the cake. Social contract theories ignore a fundamental motive for cooperation, which goes beyond self-interest, utility, or survival: the wish to cooperate with a par- ticular set of individuals rather than with another. Game theoretic approaches to justice typically take for granted the scope of the group within which “the game of justice” is played, referring to the players in thin (universal) terms as rational beings (or, to be loyal to Rawls, rational and reasonable individuals constrained by the sense of fairness). But there are numerous schemes of cooperation for any given individual, differing from each other in the scope and the identity of the 116 David Heyd other individuals with whom cooperation takes place. Utility or prudence cannot decide this scope or identity since at most it accounts for ad hoc forms of social cooperation (typically in economic enterprises or games) rather than for compre- hensive systems of social justice.7 And once we realize that the option of coop- erating with everybody is indeterminate, since, as we have shown, it can be interpreted in many ways, we have to decide on what basis the group within which the cooperative enterprise occurs is defined. In other words, cooperation is not just a given fact or condition of justice, but something to be chosen. This demonstrates the shortcoming of a Lockean theory of justice. It takes “the cake” as given, namely, natural resources in the world as given by God to all humanity to share. This is also the ground for the Lockean proviso, which takes all human beings as parties who deserve some share in the goods of nature. However, most issues of distributive justice involve the production of the goods (the baking of the cake) rather than just their consumption or use, which leaves open the question, with whom do we want to cooperate in the enterprise of production and related consumption. If God gave the natural world to humanity as a whole for its use, then we all have to share natural resources with each other, but, in the absence of such theological assumption, the fact that we happen to live on this planet does not in itself create a motive or a reason for sharing. Sharing takes place when we feel special care for others, which arises out of either natural ties or cooperative commitments. Before moving on to the positive grounding of the contractarian theory of justice, I would like to address an interesting and challenging objection to the “local” conception of the contract.8 Any restricted group of individuals can engage in a contract which would generate universal principles of distributive justice, that is, principles that apply to all human beings in the world (rather than just to the contractors). Thus, members of the group can agree to distribute the product of their common enterprise with all others, who are not members of the group, in various degrees: from a minimum that would secure international peace, through a more egalitarian sharing, to extreme forms of saintly altruism. In all these cases, the fact that the principles were agreed by a restricted group of people does not imply that their “reach” cannot be universal. Maybe this is exactly the way we expect enlightened liberal states to fix their principles of justice, namely, to apply them globally, beyond their own borders. Such a disparity between the scope of the consenting group and that of the beneficiaries of the principles agreed upon by the group is indeed possible (although, unfortunately, it tends to be of the less altruistic kind). But it does not undermine the theoretical claim made above, which was concerned merely with the way principles of justice are justified rather than with their content (or the identity of their beneficiaries). The point of contract-based principles is that they apply to the contractors only because they agreed to them (under certain idealized conditions). Therefore, they create claims and counter-claims only within the group in which the contract was made. Non-members of this group may be the beneficiaries of the contract, but have no claim or right against the contracting Justice and Solidarity 117 members. An obvious indication for it is that non-members can share the benefits of a contractual agreement of a group of people, but cannot be expected to carry the burdens of such an agreement (to which they were not party). They can enjoy transfers of wealth to them but cannot be taxed. Contract-based principles of distributive justice can therefore apply to non- members but only for some reason lying beyond the idea of pure consent. The contractors may believe, for instance, that non-members deserve some goods, a minimal standard of living, or the satisfaction of their needs. But these are substantive moral principles, which serve as the grounds for the distributive duties. All the contract does in this instance is to help decide the way the non-contractual duties of members toward non-members is to be distributed within the group of members. An obvious example would be duties of care toward animals (which are beneficiaries of these duties without being parties to the contract). A more con- troversial but still powerful example would be a society’s duties to future genera- tions. Even if future people have rights (which I doubt), they can hardly be accounted for in contractarian terms, especially if we think of future people who are just possible and whose existence is subject to our own decisions. Non- members can never be considered free riders by members of the contracting group since they are not bound by any duty of fairness. Solidarity Solidarity is a social force which contributes to the sustenance of the unity of a group of people. Like the solidity of physical bodies, it is what keeps an entity from disintegrating. Both its etymology and historical sources are French, leading back to the revolutionary idea of fraternité.9 It is intimately connected to coop- eration, that is, to intentional common enterprise, calling for a combined and coordinated action by many people. Unlike natural bonding forces of the kind of family love and care, solidarity is mediated by a commitment to an idea or a cause. In that respect, solidarity is “ideological.” Although we say that solidarity is something we feel toward or with others, this is not a raw feeling, but involves cognitive and reflective elements. Solidarity is thus to be distinguished from both family love and the companionship of friends (camaraderie) in being based on the awareness of a common cause, a worthy social goal, a sense of shared past or future destiny. Solidarity, like cooperation, is not simply given but rather chosen or constructed on the basis of certain beliefs. Solidarity has a typically cohesive effect and is often considered necessary for the success of a social struggle. Thus, solidarity is manifest in the struggle of the working class against oppression, the fight of trade unions for the amelioration of working conditions, or the effort of liberation movements of minorities to achieve recognition. Solidarity typically involves the commitment of individuals to remain loyal to the collective cause even when it means ignoring their self-interest and potential personal gain.10 In that respect, solidarity does not come naturally to us but takes a conscious effort aimed at the achievement of an impersonal goal.11 Solidarity has both descriptive 118 David Heyd and normative dimensions: it characterizes the “togetherness” of people and makes demands of loyalty to the group. Since solidarity is created in the course of a struggle for a collective cause, it is necessarily exclusive, presupposing the existence of competing causes. Unlike friendship, tribal community, and family, solidarity is a social bonding that is formed against, or at least in competition with, other groups. Richard Rorty, for example, speaks of “we” or “one of us” as the foundation of solidarity, when “we” is contrasted to “they” on the basis of a historically dependent construction rather than on any essential natural qualities.12 But this does not imply a Schmittian friend/foe model. Identification with a group is exclusionary in some sense, but not necessarily hostile. Chantal Mouffe appropriately describes solidarity as an “agonistic” (rather than “antagonistic”) basis for “we-identity.” Solidarity is a relational concept which presupposes the existence of other groups that are rivals or adversaries.13 Solidarity, I suggest, is a form of bonding, which is partly given, partly created by a group of people, on the basis of a shared past, a present interest, hopes for the future, or engagement in an enterprise directed to the realization of common values. Shame is an interesting indicator of the limited scope of solidar- ity: we can feel ashamed of what our family members do, or of the behavior of our fellow citizens and even government. We do not feel shame for what other human beings as such have done, and if we do, this is only on the assumption that there is a higher order of beings before whom we feel this shame (God, imaginary extra-terrestrial beings).14 The sources of solidarity are often circumstantial and even forced upon people. Thus, sharing a territory with people of a different culture or even “nation- ality” creates a powerful form of economic and psychological interdependence which, in turn, gives rise to a sense of solidarity or may create a normative reason for promoting solidarity. Unlike friendship or tribal identification, national soli- darity is often shown among people who may be in many respects adversaries, like national and ethnic minorities. The state responsibility of justice toward minorities is exclusive, that is, does not include members of that minority group living outside the borders of the state. Majority and minorities in a multicultural society share the same destiny in many respects, a fact that creates a sense of solidarity. Note that the historically based formation of solidarity is fully compatible with the non-historical, hypothetical nature of the Original Position (or the classical “social contracts”): the historically contingent circumstances are the conditions for the operation and scope of the thought experiment of a hypothetical agreement. One important implication of the agonistic character of solidarity is that it cannot be universal. Humanity might be the object of Kantian respect but not of identification. We identify ourselves as human beings, but we do not identify with human beings as such. The idea of a “human community” is as misleading as it is attractive.15 We could imagine indeed circumstances in which our planet is threat- ened by the invasion of a rival, non-human race, leading to the rise of “human solidarity.” But this only serves to confirm the relational analysis of the concept. Solidarity is in its essence partial, in the sense of being opposite to both universal Justice and Solidarity 119 and impartial, that is to say, it is local and biased. This does not in any way detract from the universality of moral duties or human rights.16 It only aims to distinguish between the universal level of morality and the local, solidarity-based level of certain forms of social justice. Rorty is willing to extend the application of the concept of solidarity to the universal level of “all humanity,” arguing that we feel solidarity with any human being vulnerable to suffering and humiliation.17 But this extension, I believe, is artificial, since it does not involve any shared value or cause with which people actually identify, but only a universal revulsion from pain. Furthermore, the extension goes against Rorty’s own analysis of solidarity, since sympathy and compassion with people suffering pain is not a matter of construct- ing a group of “us” on the basis of contingent historically dependent conditions but a universal natural inclination of human beings (which, unlike solidarity, is often expressed also toward animals). Solidarity, accordingly, is an interesting attitude, since it lies halfway between unmediated feelings like love or compassion and a pure rational Kantian recog- nition of the moral standing of fellow human beings who have dignity and rights. One may describe solidarity as sympathy mediated by a belief in a common project. Solidarity combines personal and impersonal components: the objects of solidarity are mostly anonymous in the sense that the subject does not personally know them. But they are also not considered as just human beings abstracted from all their individuating characteristics. We care for people with whom we feel solidarity, but do so on the basis of their belonging to “our” group fighting for a certain goal rather than as just individual human beings. The view I am proposing here is that just distribution is one such social goal and hence it both presupposes and reinforces solidarity.18 This combination of a historical “given” with a self- determined commitment to a cause is constitutive of solidarity. It should be noted that the justification of the particularistic aspect of distributive justice is not grounded in universal terms (such as the general efficiency of dividing the world into smaller units in the attempt to promote overall justice in the world). It is rather that the conditions of the applicability of contract-based justice are particularistic. Durkheim’s work on solidarity can help us see this point. The modern phe- nomenon of the division of labor is (surprisingly) associated by Durkheim with the development of social solidarity. For Durkheim, division of labor is not merely a means for the promotion of individual welfare through increased production, but a moral value in itself. It touches upon the deep foundations of the very existence of social bonding, since it involves mutual complement rather than mere egoistic exchange. It is more similar to Aristotelian friendship than to cooperation in game-theoretic contexts.19 Mechanical solidarity, for Durkheim, is created on the basis of likeness and is primarily expressed by the criminal law of society, its collective passionate reaction to crime, the common response of people sharing a common conscience. Organic solidarity, in contrast, is grounded in the differences between people which call for cooperation and division of labor. It is the recog- nition of the importance of the different functioning of different parts of society, analogous to the harmonious functioning of parts of an organism.20 For our 120 David Heyd purposes, we should emphasize that Durkheim contrasts modern society, based on the functional division of labor, to traditional society, based on kinship or natural tribal affinity. Durkheim is convinced that modern, organic solidarity is no weaker than its traditional predecessor. Furthermore, organic solidarity is expressed in institutions rather than in feelings, primarily in the laws of contract, family, property, and labor. The apparently impersonal structure of social relations creates the mutual commitment of solidarity. Durkheim’s analysis of solidarity and the division of labor can be used to analyze the problem of the social contract raised at the beginning of this article. Even if the terms of the contract itself are described as completely impersonal, self-interested, and impartial, the motive for entering the contract in the first place should be described in more particularistic terms, namely, the Durkheimian drive to complement one another, to cooperate with others in achieving a morally valuable aim. The original position is not only the thought-experiment in which the prin- ciples of just social cooperation are articulated; it is itself a cooperative enterprise, and as such it must have a motive. As in any game, the rules are impersonal and impartial, but the motivation to play the game with particular people cannot be purely impersonal or abstract. Solidarity is such a motivation and operates in a dialectical way: we engage in just cooperation with people about whom we care and, in turn, the cooperation itself reinforces our solidarity with them. This bidirectional operation of solidarity can be demonstrated in the cooperation of the “working class,” or in the mutual commitment of members of a trade union, in Durkheim’s idea of division of labor, or—in my argument—in distributive justice. One should not be misled into thinking that solidarity is a communitarian idea which serves as a basis for a communitarian conception of justice. Durkheim’s concept of solidarity relates to a modern Gesellschaft rather than to a traditional Gemeinschaft.21 It is accordingly expressed in institutional arrangements rather than in compassionate feelings or shared traditional practices. As Chantal Mouffe proposes, it assumes common values but no agreement on their ranking. The ranking is left for political negotiation within the group, but solidarity is the bonding of the group within which politics takes place.22 I may add that in social contract theory unanimity is a condition only in the agreement on the foundational terms of political legitimacy and the principles of justice; once political society is established, the rule of decision making is typically majoritarian and allows for pluralism and competing goals.23 Solidarity does not necessarily generate an egalitarian system of justice, but it does explain the equal weight given to the parties in the initial contract. Solidarity is, therefore, the bond which unites the partners to the contract in their commitment to decision-making procedures in conflict situations typical of heterogeneous societies.24 In other words, we must first decide the scope of the group within which we count heads and whose majority we follow. Majority, like justice, cannot fix the size of the group within which it operates. So it seems that although liberalism in its universal view of moral relations must be suspicious of the idea of solidarity (and indeed this idea has been much Justice and Solidarity 121 more popular in socialism, feminism, and communitarianism),25 it nevertheless presupposes solidarity as the condition for the social contract. This could also serve as an answer to Brian Barry’s query: How can Rawls’s contract take place in a particular society if the contractors are supposed to be mutually disinter- ested?26 Disinterest is one of the conditions in the original position, but it does not and cannot be a condition for entering the original position. The State It is no coincidence that the idea of contract-based legitimation of govern- ment, and hence of political justice, was developed more or less simultaneously with the rise of the modern state. The state is the most extensive social framework in which principles of distributive justice can be meaningfully applied. Smaller- scale social associations have their own distributive norms, but they cover a more restricted scope of goods and burdens to be distributed. Voluntary associations, like clubs and games, define the scope of distributions in a relatively precise way, but cover only little of the main goods and burdens of human life. Natural associations, like families and tribal communities, control much wider systems of distributions and deserts, but the basis of these systems is not voluntary. The social contract is a device for generating principles of justice that are both voluntary and comprehensive in their content. The state is the natural locus for such principles since it enjoys sovereignty, that is, the power to enforce the contract in a wide array of social issues: it distributes the burdens of military service and taxation as well as the benefits of many public and private goods. It is the most effective framework for the division of labor. Critics of the modern state, like Habermas, argue that the state is an imagined community (in Benedict Anderson’s terms), a construction invented in order to create social solidarity where there is no cultural or ethnic basis for a common political identity. Max Pensky says that “ ‘Nation’ consists of an imaginary soli- darity among strangers that cements the otherwise fragile bonds of reasonable cooperation.” Furthermore, he adds, the difficulty of creating solidarity for the achievement of abstract republican ideas makes the nation-state “ ‘double coded’ or indeed Janus faced.”27 On the one hand, the universalism associated with political and moral equality requires the rejection of all particularistic loyalties; on the other, national solidarity defines itself “against” the other. There is, in other words, an inner contradiction between what might be called inward universal egalitarianism and outward particularism. Now, my approach to the relationship between justice and the state considers this tension between the exclusivism and inclusivism of the state as exactly its asset as the framework of distributive justice. For it embodies a form of solidarity that arises out of certain historical factors (like shared territory, common experience, sometimes a dominant language and culture), and it applies egalitarian principles and impartial concern to its own citizens. 122 David Heyd So David Miller is right in claiming that “without a common national identity, there is nothing to hold citizens together, no reason for extending the role just to these people and not to others.”28 But this in no way entails a communitarian view of either the identity or the normative basis of the state. For these are at least partly derived from the very enterprise of instituting agreed-upon principles of justice. There is no circularity in such a characterization of the state, although it is dialectic in nature: it originates in some form of a historical process, but is then reinforced by the sense of the common endeavor to establish and maintain a just society. This is typically the case with the Constitution-based identity of the American nation.29 Even Brian Barry, a passionate advocate of cosmopolitanism, concedes that national identity requires more than a passport and that it is con- stituted by “civic nationality,” namely, the identification with society’s social institutions and the recognition of a common good. The problem with Barry’s view is that it is not clear what he means by common good: is it a universal good (which would make “nationality” vacuous), or is it particular to the national group (which would weaken his argument that political entities have no moral value and are only instrumental in promoting universal values such as human rights)?30 Solidarity-based justice does not exclusively express itself in the framework of the nation-state. But it should be noted that when it crosses national boundaries it is not constituted by a contract. Thus, the solidarity of the working classes in the communist sense is the mutual commitment of people in different countries to the transformation of the social system into a more just one. But justice here means a substantive ideal scheme of power relations and distributions rather than a set of principles generated by an ideal contract. On the other hand, the call for social solidarity of the middle class with the unemployed and the poor within a given society is a hallmark of the welfare state. It is a demand for the special concern of people for their fellow citizens with whom they cooperate politically (in the democratic vote, in defending the country, in producing its wealth, in perpetuating its cultural heritage, and of course in sharing its territory).31 Can Justice Be Globalized? As I indicated at the beginning of this article, theoretical attempts to extend the scope of application of distributive justice across nations arose more or less simultaneously with attempts to extend it across generations. Of the two extrapo- lations, it was believed that the intergenerational (“vertical”) is more intractable than the international because of the crucial difference between possible and actual people. Duties of justice toward future people cannot be fully determined due to the indeterminate number of people who are going to be both subjects and objects of those duties. Not only do we not know the relevant demographic data; the number of future people is to a large extent determined by the economic and demographic policies which stand to be chosen. This is a logical problem for which there is no coherent answer. On the other hand, global justice in the “horizontal” sense concerns actual people whose number and identity are both Justice and Solidarity 123 given and known (not to speak of their needs and preferences which can only be guessed in the intergenerational case). In that respect, at least philosophically, the case for transnational justice is much easier to make.32 However, if my argument about the conceptual connection between justice and solidarity is persuasive, then it seems that the intergenerational application of justice is more natural than its global counterpart. For it is definitely the case that our concern for “our own” descendants (and respect for our predecessors) carries more weight than our concern for contemporary strangers. The former are conceived as partners to the social cooperation of our polity, for whose welfare we strive, and we expect them to contribute to a common enterprise that is transgenerational in nature. It is much more natural to view the state as extending in time than to see it as a global entity comprising all actual (present) human beings. We feel solidarity with our (future) children and grandchildren but not with our remote contemporaries. A single generational “slice” of a community is not self-sufficient in the sense that we cannot invest meaning in our private and collective life without the perspective of both the past and the future of the social project in which we are engaged. Yet, the transgenerational continuous existence of a community makes perfect sense, even independently of other, contempora- neous communities. However, there are a few powerful philosophical voices which press the case for global justice no less than for intergenerational justice. Impartiality means that we should take the geographical index as no less arbitrary than the temporal. Much of the debate revolves around the possibility of applying Rawls’s difference principle globally, and whether Rawls himself is correct in insisting that it can be done only in a limited way. Charles Beitz is one of the first and most fervent advocates of global justice. He argues first against the Hobbesian “realist” view that considers the international realm as lying beyond the grasp of moral judg- ment. Rawls’s difference principle should be applied also globally, ideally on the individual level (i.e., not constrained by intra-national arrangements), or at least on the national level (constraining any deviation from international equality by concern for the worst-off country). Beitz’s cosmopolitan approach grounds the duties of international redistribution not in the duty of assistance but in that of justice.33 For sovereignty, unlike autonomy, cannot serve as a defense against sharing a country’s resources with others. Unlike natural talents, which are not subject to redistribution, being constitutive of our personal identity, natural resources do not constitute collective or national identities, and hence their actual distribution in the world should be considered morally arbitrary and consequently subject to redistribution on the basis of egalitarian justice.34 This appears to be a forceful argument, but we must remember that some important natural resources (even oil) are not like manna, simply there to be used, but have to be searched for and extracted from nature, that is to say, they have value only when a cooperative human activity transforms them into consumable goods. Again, the cake, even when it looks “natural,” has to be baked before being eaten and hence its just distribution is a matter of deserts that accrue to the 124 David Heyd participants in its production. Indeed, this might not apply to some primary goods like health, in which desert or right is not derived from the contribution to its “production.” But even in this case, we view the distribution of health services as part of an overall scheme of social cooperation in which the ability to provide these services is dependent on the productivity in a particular group of people and on their particular order of priorities. Beitz also points out that sovereignty cannot be a morally relevant constraint on global distributions. The boundaries of a political sovereign entity cannot be left to individuals to decide, since—as was argued at the beginning of this article—who will decide the scope of the group of individuals who will make the decision? However, I think Beitz draws the wrong cosmopolitan conclusion from this puzzle of bootstrapping: it cannot mean that all human beings should take part in deciding the principles of just distribution, since that already prejudges the issue of the correct extent of the contract and in any case leaves the range of “all” indeterminate. For this reason, Beitz’s demand to leave the facts about national affiliation under the veil of ignorance when engaging in the thought-experiment of the original position undermines the very possibility or motive for a contractual agreement.35 For when I choose to enter the original position, I want at least to know with whom, with what kind of people I am going to hold justice relations. Rawls, in his later writings, came to the conclusion that distributive justice, particularly the difference principle, applies only on the domestic level, in “bounded societies” which are self-sufficient transgenerational systems of coop- eration into which individuals are born and in which they usually die. Although there are transnational principles of justice, they first apply only to “peoples” (rather than to individuals), and second they are limited in content to raising other societies (or peoples) to the threshold conditions of justice, that is, the ability to maintain just domestic institutions.36 There is, therefore, no duty of justice of equality toward either the worst-off societies or the worst-off individuals in the world. The main reason for this restriction of justice to the domestic sphere is that societies are to a large extent responsible for their own economic conditions, which are the function of free choice regarding demographic planning and other cultural values (such as the rate of savings for future generations, or religious arrangements of property and power distribution). I want to reinforce the Rawlsian opposition to the globalization of justice. Rawls points out that different societies might agree on different principles for domestic justice, for example, non-liberal (but “decent-hierarchical”) societies would not accept the difference principle. But even assuming that (ideally) all societies in the world agreed on the difference principle, this would not mean a global application of that principle. For each society is at best motivated by the idea of advancing the welfare of its worst off members, rather than the world’s. This can be illustrated by an analogy. If two societies adhere to the (same) majority principle, it does not mean that they wish to follow the joint majority of the two societies! Even the other clause of Rawls’s second principle of justice, the equality of opportunity, is social specific; it is artificial to think of giving every- Justice and Solidarity 125 body in the world equal opportunity in the competition for jobs, education, or political participation. But of course, these analogous cases of distributive justice—majoritarianism and equal opportunity—should be distinguished from the commitment to human rights: two countries which sign the Geneva Conven- tion assume a universal responsibility to prevent war crimes in general, not just “their” war crimes. The same applies to natural duties like those of assistance to starving people. So the local character of justice does not derive solely from the culture-dependent nature of its principles, but more fundamentally from the local basis or motive of the cooperation which it is meant to regulate. It is interesting to note that while on the domestic level the contract includes everybody, regardless of his or her comprehensive moral views, on the interna- tional level a contract is made, according to Rawls, only with peoples of a certain kind, namely, “liberal and decent,” and not with “outlaw and burdened” societies. This indicates that any contract must be motivated by some deep motive, such as solidarity, which operates in different ways in the domestic and the international contexts. In the domestic case, it is the motive of self-interested individuals to further their welfare by cooperating on a fair basis with people with whom they feel solidarity. In the international case, it is the motive of promoting justice, peace, and security which leads societies to principles of non-aggression, trade relations, and aid. Indeed, states as such do not feel solidarity with each other, but peoples often do share such feelings (e.g., the United States and Britain in World War II). However, this kind of solidarity leads to alliances and agreements of mutual interest rather than to relations of distributive justice. These agreements, unlike the domestic social contract, are actual rather than hypothetical, and are binding like promises rather than as a matter of fairness. Both the domestic and the global approaches to justice take the individual as the essential unit. Although Rawlsian contract theory is conceived as a mere political construction, the idea of justice as fairness must take the individual as a non-arbitrary, metaphysical foundation in the theory. It is only the scope of the group of contracting individuals, which is left contingent (depending on the kind of solidarity frameworks that happen to develop in history). In other words, individualism is a philosophically necessary assumption of contract-based justice. However, the international approach addresses relations between peoples, states, or societies, which are not metaphysically fixed units, but rather empirically determined entities, and worse, entities whose scope and bounds are themselves partly objects of normative decision. Now, denying that justice applies globally does not mean that there are no moral principles governing international relations. There are natural duties which obligate both individuals and governments, primarily the duty of aid. People who lack the basic necessities, like food and water, immunization or shelter, have a legitimate expectation to be assisted. Unlike the concern for the worst off in society on the domestic level which is based on equality, the concern for starving people in other societies is based on want, on deprivation of universal human means of survival. Human rights and international law are also to be respected 126 David Heyd irrespective of national boundaries and cooperative agreements. So are the duties of compensation for past exploitation or oppression, which are measures of corrective justice. On the level of states, non-aggression and the respect for trade and other agreements are principles that must be respected. But these are all principles of a different sort than those of fair distribution (like the difference principle). Their justification lies in human nature, rationality, or sympathy, rather than in ideal contractual agreement. Indeed, there are also specifically distributive problems that call for global solutions, like the distribution of the burdens associated with fighting global warming, the ozone threat, the dwindling of the fish population in the oceans, the disappearing rain forests, world epidemics, and so on. There are goods which in their nature are global, that is, cannot be linked to any particular sovereign territory. These problems can only be addressed by sovereign states in the world through mutual agreement. But like international trade agreements or mutual disarmament treaties, these do not relate to “the basic structure of society,” but are of an ad hoc nature. They reflect the power relations and interests of the actual parties rather than the idea of fair distribution (although this does not mean that the agreements are free from moral constraints, like the prevention of exploitation or the use of force). Unlike the “basic structure of domestic society,” world order is expected to achieve primarily peace, stability, and mutual advantage, rather than the fair distribution of primary goods. The aim of this article is modest. It does not intend to claim that human action on the global level is free from moral constraints. It does not purport to relieve either individuals or states from duties toward members of other societies. It only tries to show that one of the most powerful methods of justifying normative arrangements, that of the social contract, cannot account for the sphere of global moral relations. If we adhere to a liberal view of justice as a consent-based system of norms created under the strict methodology of a hypothetical contract, then we will have to view international relations and global distributions as deriving their justification from a different source than that of the contract. Justice, particularly in its distributive sense, should be kept as a separate category from natural duties, rational ad hoc agreements, impartial solutions of conflicts, and respect for human rights. This article tries to show that the distinctive feature of contract-based justice is a prior sense or motive which makes the contract possible and defines its scope. This sense is here called solidarity. The answer to Hobbes’s perplexity— how can a multitude of people institute a commonwealth through a covenant?—is quite simple: the covenanting people are not really a multitude to begin with. This article was written during my fellowship at the Institute for Advanced Studies of the Hebrew University of Jerusalem. Justice and Solidarity 127 Notes 1 Alongside numerous philosophers following Rawls, I have discussed that issue in some detail in my Genethics: Moral Issues in the Creation of People (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1992). 2 John Locke, Two Treatises of Government, ed. Peter Laslett (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988), 331. 3 Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, ed. Richard Tuck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996), 121. 4 For an early discussion in our period of democracy’s inability to determine its scope, see Frederick G. Whelan, “Democratic Theory and the Boundary Problem,” Nomos 25 (1983): 13–47. 5 Cf. Bernard Yack, “Popular Sovereignty and Nationalism,” Political Theory 29 (2001): 529. 6 Sen strongly advocates this shift from the model of consent to that of impartial arbitration. And he is right in his belief that a model of impartial decision can avoid the logical problem of a contract with future people or with potential members of a given polity in deciding the scope of membership. However, I am not sure how the conditions for impartial decision can be speci- fied. The whole point of consent-based legitimation is that it avoids the interminable contro- versies about what constitutes impartiality by letting the parties to the conflict agree on the principles of justice. Impartiality, like neutrality and the “ideal observer,” is hard to define without appealing to substantive values or positions, while the fairness of a process of agree- ment is less controversial. Amartya Sen, “Justice across Borders,” in Global Justice and Tran- snational Politics, eds. Pablo De Greiff and Ciaran Cronin (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2002), 45–46. 7 This seems to go against Russell Hardin’s view in his One for All: The Logic of Group Conflict (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1995), particularly chap. 3. I do not deny that self- interest and group identification are often “congruent” and that such identification may cease when costs to the individual become very high (p. 47). However, this does not prove that self-interest can be the exclusive and exhaustive grounds for the formation of a political entity with its own system of justice (even if we include under “self-interest” altruistic motivations such as the interests of others). Hardin’s main concerns with the rationality of identification are contexts of ethnic or national conflicts (where it is natural indeed to approach the issue of belonging from the instru- mental or self-interested point of view); but my focus here is on the context of distributive justice in which the promotion of interest within a fair system of binding rules (rather than pure self-interest) is sought. 8 The objection was raised by one of the anonymous referees of this article. I am grateful in general to his or her detailed and incisive comments. 9 It is interesting to note that most of the major philosophical literature on the subject of solidarity is French (and then German), rather than English and American: Auguste Comte, Emile Durkheim, and Jürgen Habermas, to name a few of the important writers on solidarity. Rawls considers the difference principle as a manifestation of fraternity (A Theory of Justice [Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971], 106), but does not analyze its nature. 10 Loyalty is closely related to solidarity in its being “necessary to form a community of reciprocally caring people, committed to counting each other as equal in their common project.” George Fletcher, Loyalty (New York: Oxford University Press, 1993), 20. I follow Fletcher in the idea that “loyalty is a critical element in a theory of justice; for we invariably need some basis for group cohesion, for caring about others, . . . as partners in a common venture” (p. 21). However, soli- darity seems to me to better capture the conditions of justice than loyalty, since it is not a straightforward duty (sometimes even overriding other moral duties), but rather a presupposition of justice (though it has some weak normative force). Solidarity is a less personal relation, and, unlike loyalty, does not apply to marital relations or to the relations between man and God. The opposite of solidarity is not treason or treachery, but simply indifference. It is essentially reciprocal (which is not the case with loyalty): I cannot feel solidarity with a group in which no one else feels solidarity, since the group is (partly) constituted by the sense of solidarity. This also explains why I can be loyal to my (true) self, but cannot be said to feel solidarity with myself. 128 David Heyd 11 Some philosophers distinguish between natural solidarity (of family or community members) and “project-related solidarity” (based on what I refer to as a common cause). See Klaus Peter Rippe, “Distinguishing Solidarity,” Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 1 (1998): 355–73. My approach, however, involves features of both kinds of solidarity. As Joel Feinberg has noted, solidarity consists not only of the overlap of shared specialized interests (like in corporations), but also of a community of interests (like in a family or a nation). See Joel Feinberg, Doing and Deserving (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1970), 233–34. It is interesting that Feinberg suggests an argument concerning retributive justice which runs parallel to the one outlined here concerning distributive justice: collective responsibility can be imposed on a group of people only when there is an “antecedent solidarity” between them (ibid., 240–41). 12 Richard Rorty, Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), 189–98. 13 Chantal Mouffe, “Politics, Democratic Action, and Solidarity,” Inquiry 38 (1995): 99–108. 14 This very exceptional sense of shame was developed by Karl Jaspers in his moving, post-Holocaust essay on German guilt. Metaphysical guilt is felt by human beings for crimes other human beings have perpetrated. It is felt in the face of God and is close to the sense of shame in belonging to the same species as the perpetrators. Karl Jaspers, The Question of German Guilt, trans. E. B. Ashton (New York: Capricorn Books, 1961). Cf. Feinberg, Doing and Deserving, 236–37, where guilt and shame are presented as indicators of solidarity. 15 Avishai Margalit has pointed out to me the deceptive and manipulative idea of “the family of man” (famously used as the title of a 1950s exhibition of photography). 16 Richard Miller, “Cosmopolitan Respect and Patriotic Concern,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 27 (1998): 202–22. Equal respect applies to all human beings as such; concern applies in more local groups, like peoples. 17 Rorty, Contingency, 192. 18 For a very close view, see Véronique Munoz-Dardé, “Fraternity and Justice,” in Solidarity, ed. Kurt Bayertz (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1999), 87: “It may appear that the ‘spirit of fraternity and benevo- lence’ must already exist between citizens as a precondition of social justice, and that the difference principle depends upon a conception of the good that makes each member of the political community want to identify with and care for other citizens.” See also Margaret Canovan, Nationhood and Political Theory (Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, 1996), chap. 4, appropriately entitled “Social Justice: Looking after Our People.” 19 Emile Durkheim, The Division of Labor in Society, trans. George Simpson (New York: Free Press, 1964), 63–64. 20 Ibid., 127–29. 21 Cf. Ulrich K. Preuss, “National, Supernational and International Solidarity,” in Solidarity, ed. Kurt Bayertz (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1999), 283. 22 Mouffe, “Politics,” 103. According to Craig Mataresse, Sartre’s idea of solidarity is based on the individual’s pledge not to betray or defect from society. Being based on choice, it is contrasted to Hegel’s communitarian and organicist view of political society, in which the social bonding is not mediated by a principle or a value. See Craig Mataresse, “Solidarity and Fear: Hegel and Sartre on the Mediations of Reciprocity,” Philosophy Today 45 (2001): 43. 23 I have dealt in detail with this two-tier structure of contract theory in the context of the majority principle. See David Heyd, “Counting Heads or Casting Lots: The Lottery Challenge to Majority Rule,” Iyyun 53 (2004): 3–26. 24 Charles Taylor has argued that an egalitarian democratic regime requires a higher degree of citizen solidarity than a traditional hierarchical society in which the issue of the minority acceptance of the majority decision does not arise. 25 Kurt Bayertz, “Four Uses of Solidarity,” in Solidarity, ed. Bayertz (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1999), 3–28. This article is an important contribution to the taxonomy and analysis of the concept of solidarity. Justice and Solidarity 129 26 Brian Barry, Theories of Justice (London: Harvester, 1989), 181–82. This resolves the tension pointed out by Barry between Rawls’s commitment to impartiality on the domestic level and his acceptance of mutual advantage as guiding international relations. 27 Max Pensky, “Cosmopolitanism and the Solidarity Problem: Habermas on National and Cultural Identities,” Constellations 7 (2000): 66. 28 David Miller, “Community and Citizenship,” in Communitarianism and Individualism, ed. S. Avineri and A. de-Shalit (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992), 94. See also On Nationality (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995), 61–62. Andrew Mason takes issue with Miller and claims that a weaker sense of belonging, not necessarily “national,” is a sufficient condition for distributive justice. Andrew Mason, Community, Solidarity, and Belonging (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), 134–35. 29 Craig Calhoun, “Constitutional Patriotism and the Public Sphere,” in Global Justice and Transna- tional Politics, eds. Pablo De Greiff and Ciaran Cronin (Cambridge: MIT Press, 2002), 290. Calhoun argues that the public sphere is constructed through discourse, that is, it is a product of “solidarity and choice.” I am told that a major factor in contemporary Swedish national identity is the commitment of its citizens to the Swedish welfare system and their pride in it. This would be a perfect example of the way justice plays a role in the creation of national solidarity. 30 Brian Barry, Culture and Inequality (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2001), 80ff. 31 For a very compelling description of the multifarious ways in which citizens are united by “common sympathies,” see John Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), 23 and particularly note 17 in which he quotes extensively J. S. Mill on “Nationality” and its grounds. 32 See Lukas Meyer, “Justice, Intergenerational,” in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Edward Zalta. URL: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/justice-intergenerational. 33 Charles Beitz, Political Theory and International Relations (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979), 128. 34 Thomas Nagel, in a recently published article, also wonders about the moral arbitrariness of local borderlines but ultimately sides with a form of non-universalistic, “associative” model of justice. See Thomas Nagel, “The Problem of Global Justice,” Philosophy and Public Affairs 33 (2005): 113–47. 35 Charles Beitz, “International Liberalism and Distributive Justice: A Survey of Recent Thought,” World Politics 51 (1999): 269–96. 36 Rawls, The Law of Peoples. 130 David Heyd http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/justice-intergenerational work_mditi344dbbnllpyv4p6zokjma ---- Microsoft Word - Access_to_Justice_and_Litigation_Saraceno_SSRN WP UvA-DARE is a service provided by the library of the University of Amsterdam (https://dare.uva.nl) UvA-DARE (Digital Academic Repository) Justice: greater access, lower costs Saraceno, M. DOI 10.2139/ssrn.2383864 Publication date 2014 Document Version Submitted manuscript Link to publication Citation for published version (APA): Saraceno, M. (2014). Justice: greater access, lower costs. (Amsterdam Center for Law & Economics Working Paper; No. 2014-01). University of Amsterdam. https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2383864 General rights It is not permitted to download or to forward/distribute the text or part of it without the consent of the author(s) and/or copyright holder(s), other than for strictly personal, individual use, unless the work is under an open content license (like Creative Commons). Disclaimer/Complaints regulations If you believe that digital publication of certain material infringes any of your rights or (privacy) interests, please let the Library know, stating your reasons. In case of a legitimate complaint, the Library will make the material inaccessible and/or remove it from the website. Please Ask the Library: https://uba.uva.nl/en/contact, or a letter to: Library of the University of Amsterdam, Secretariat, Singel 425, 1012 WP Amsterdam, The Netherlands. You will be contacted as soon as possible. Download date:06 Apr 2021 https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2383864 https://dare.uva.nl/personal/pure/en/publications/justice-greater-access-lower-costs(00b3b774-53f0-42f3-9667-aec2be978011).html https://doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2383864 Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2383864 JUSTICE: GREATER ACCESS, LOWER COSTS Margherita Saraceno Amsterdam Law School Legal Studies Research Paper No. 2014-06 Amsterdam Center for Law & Economics Working Paper Paper No. 2014-01 Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2383864 Justice: Greater Access, Lower Costs Margherita Saraceno♣ January 21, 2014 Abstract Litigation imposes large costs on society; this justifies settlement considerations. In any case, access to justice is critical to socioeconomic development; as such, it needs to be balanced with litigation minimization. This study examines the tradeoff between litigation and access to justice and explicitly elucidates their relationship. In considering access issues, this study finds that the outcomes of policies that affect parties’ litigation decisions partially depart from those in the standard literature. For instance, increasing parties’ litigation costs does not necessarily promote settlement in the shadow of the court. Rather, effects depend on the elasticity of the demand for legal remedies. Furthermore, even while pushing litigation, enhancing access to justice is efficient as long as the claimant’s marginal propensity to litigate is smaller than the social opportunity-cost of access to justice. This finding offers further insight into the suitability of litigation subsidization through legal aid. JEL classification: K41. Keywords: access to justice, litigation, settlement, elasticity. _____________________________________________________________________ ♣Amsterdam Center for Law and Economics, University of Amsterdam and DEMS, University of Milano- Bicocca. Roetersstraat 11, 1018 WB Amsterdam, Netherlands. Phone: +31 (0)20 525 7164; Fax: +31 (0)20 525 5318; Email: m.saraceno@uva.nl. Corresponding author. This research has received funding from the People Programme (Marie Curie Actions) of the European Union's Seventh Framework Programme (FP7/2007-2013) under REA grant agreement n° 298470. I wish to thank Giuseppe Dari-Mattiacci, Iljoong Kim, Eric Langlais, Avraham Tabbach, Josephine van Zeben, Abraham L. Wickelgren, and the participants of the AEDE Conference 2013 (Granada), the CLEA Conference 2013 (Toronto), the GLEA Conference 2013 (Lugano), and the LIEN-Nanterre seminar (Paris) for the useful suggestions. The usual disclaimers apply. Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2383864 1   1. Introduction Disputes naturally emerge in every complex society. All of the parties to a dispute are directly affected by the events that gave rise to such dispute, and thus, they all tend to be interested in resolving them. However, disputes and their resolution are not purely private problems; they also constitute a social problem, as unresolved disputes produce negative externalities for the whole of society. In fact, when claimants simply “give up” because legal remedies are for some reason inaccessible, major social consequences emerge, including a sense of impunity, a lack of trust in institutions, underdeterrence, and increased uncertainty within the legal system. In extreme situations, when legal remedies are missing or inaccessible, conflicts can lead to severe consequences for the parties involved; widespread disorder and even violence can arise. Conversely, when access to justice is guaranteed, justiciable problems can be resolved through legal remedies such as in-court litigation or settlement (in a broad sense). For these reasons, effective and full access to justice is considered a crucial element in socioeconomic development and social security. Even the most developed legal systems struggle with ensuring citizens access to justice, since a significant number of claimants continue to be systematically excluded from legal remedies. (See, for example, the Access to Justice Initiative by the U.S. Department of Justice, the Initiative in Support of Access to Justice by the Department of Justice of Canada, the Australian Government Strategic Framework for Access to Justice, and the Access to Justice Agenda by the European Union Agency for Fundamental Rights.) Besides access to justice, policymakers have highlighted a further problem related to dispute resolution. In-court litigation is extremely costly for society, and excessive amounts of litigation result in judicial diseconomies and increased court workloads, eventually exacerbating inefficiencies. Despite the dearth of internationally comparable indicators concerning public expenditure vis-à-vis the judiciary, the public budget allocated to the various justice systems remains relevant.1 Policymakers are acutely aware of the need to ensure, and in some cases enhance, access to justice while keeping judiciary costs low. This problem is aggravated by the need to curb public spending in a time of financial crisis, since litigation accounts for most of the judicial spending. The academic literature usually analyzes these two problems—namely, obstacles to access to justice, and excessive litigation—separately, despite their evident interconnections. This study attempts to overcome this shortcoming in the literature by taking a unitary approach to the relationship between litigation and access to justice.                                                              1 For instance, in 2010, the annual approved budget allocated to the judiciary in the United States was USD 6.8 billion; across the European Union, the per-country average was EUR 2.8 billion, with a maximum of EUR 14.2 billion in the United Kingdom and a minimum of EUR 0.08 billion in Cyprus. Data are not directly comparable, since budgets can include a variety of statements depending on the country. See the Administrative Office of the U.S. Courts (2012) and CEPEJ (2012). 2   Starting from a standard law and economics setting (Bebchuk 1984; Nalebuff 1987), the problem of dispute resolution is modeled from both the micro perspective (i.e., parties’ choices) and the aggregated perspective of the social planner. The resulting framework allows us to analyze how policies—including administrative fees related to going to court, additional penalties and punitive damages, and legal aid—affect access to justice, litigation, and finally, the social costs of dispute resolution. The main results of this study can be summarized as follows. Dispute selection for trial. Taking into account the dimension of access to justice, the model used herein reconsiders some of the usual results found in the law and economics literature on litigation and the settlement rate. In particular, we find that higher claimant litigation costs discourage both settlement and litigation. Actually, every claimant who “gives up” because of excessive litigation cost neither settles nor litigates. Increasing the value at stake ambiguously affects settlement because of two combined effects: some claims shift from the sample of those settled to the sample of those litigated; others start to be settled, rather than remain unresolved. Finally, in some circumstances, the defendant costs play no role in determining the type of legal solution that is actually adopted. In particular, when the claimant must bear litigation costs that are relatively higher than those of the defendant, the selection of the preferred legal solution is driven mainly by the former. For claims in the shadow of the court, the model shows that changes in costs and amounts at stake affect settlement and litigation rates, depending on the elasticity of the demand for legal remedies. Litigation and access to justice. Improving access to justice will necessarily increase the number of litigation instances; this raises a relevant policy tradeoff. However, guaranteeing the access to justice of socially meritorious claims, even at the cost of pushing litigation, is always efficient. Intuitively, thanks to settlement, one additional claim’s access to justice results in less than one additional claim in litigation. Therefore, it is efficient to improve access to justice, as long as the claimant’s marginal propensity to litigate remains smaller than the social opportunity-cost of access to justice. Policy implications. The model used herein illustrates the tradeoff between promoting access to justice and discouraging litigation, through policies that result in larger litigation costs for claimants or an increased amount at stake (e.g., punitive damages). Additional penalties and fees levied on the defendant can be either wholly effective or ineffective, depending on the economic involvement of the defendant in the lawsuit. In particular, such policies can discourage litigation without affecting access to justice, except when the defendant must bear litigation costs that are so low that the decision to litigate or settle is in fact driven by the claimant. With respect to legal aid, the model shows that it is efficient to subsidize litigation as long as the standardized rate of litigation is lower than the social opportunity- costs of access to justice. 3   The remainder of this paper is organized as follows. Section 2 provides a brief overview of the literature. Section 3 presents the model and its policy implications, with particular attention being devoted to legal aid. Section 4 provides concluding remarks. 2. Background and related literature This section attempts to summarize briefly the main literature contributions, an understanding of which can be useful in framing the potential tradeoff between litigation and access to justice. Most studies generally focus either on litigation dynamics or on access to justice. The former topic constitutes a broad strand of law and economics literature, while the latter has mainly been investigated from either a comparative law or a political economy perspective. 2.1. Litigation versus settlement (in the shadow of the court) The traditional literature on litigation and settlement bargaining is vast and mainly based on a game-theory approach. A more recent and comprehensive survey of this topic is provided by Daughety and Reinganum (2012), who systematize a large number of contributions ranging from axiomatic models to those based on a strategic approach.2 Mainly, this kind of literature analyzes the reasons why parties in conflict fail in their negotiations and, subsequently, their cases go in trial. In fact, settlement acts as a sort of filter by selecting some of the cases for the court while resolving the others. Although litigation is able to produce positive externalities in terms of deterrence and reductions in law- uncertainty through precedent,3 it is generally considered wasteful, both for the parties involved and for society. For this reason, the literature mainly focuses on the capacity of bargaining to reduce the litigation rate.4 Pretrial bargaining has been modeled both as a sequential game (with one, multiple, or infinite rounds) and, less frequently, as a simultaneous game.5 According to the literature, the main source of settlement breakdown and consequent litigation is the persistence of the differential expectations of the parties on trial outcomes, even after bargaining interaction.6 This persistence has been explained while                                                              2 Axiomatic models usually assume perfect or imperfect but symmetric information. Solutions are typically cooperative. Strategic models emphasize the strategic interaction of parties, the Bayesian updating of their beliefs, and noncooperative solutions. See Cooter and Rubinfeld (1989). 3 See Che and Yi (1993); Dari-Mattiacci and Daffeins (2007); Landes (1971); Polinsky and Rubienfeld (1988); Posner (1973); and Shavell (1982), (1997), and (1999). 4 Besides the literature on settlement, see also contributions vis-à-vis alternative dispute resolution (e.g., Shavell 1995). 5 Settlement is often designed as an ultimatum game in one round, as seen in, for example, Bebchuk (1984), P’ng (1983), and Reinganum and Wilde (1986). On multiple-round settlement, see Spier (1992) and Wang et al. (1994). On infinite rounds, see Rubinstein (1982) and Yildiz (2003). On simultaneous games, see Daughety and Reinganum (1993) and Friedman and Wittman (2006). 6 In her extensive survey, Spier (2007) summarizes further explanations of settlement failure, including indivisible claims, nonpecuniary gains from going to trial, friction in the liability system, and the existence of multiple claimants. 4   assuming either different and inconsistent priors (typically in axiomatic models), or asymmetric information between litigants (in strategic models).7  A common lesson can be drawn from the broad array of specific models on settlement: both asymmetries between parties in terms of information or beliefs and low litigation costs give rise to a positive rate of litigation, and then a certain level of inefficiency owing to some use of a costly trial. From this perspective, any model that is designed as a one-sided, asymmetric-information ultimatum game seems to provide sufficiently robust and general insights (Daughety and Reinganum 2012, section 12.4).  Although the theoretical literature on settlement is immense, a great proportion of the studies therein assume that the claimant has a credible threat to litigate against the defendant. This means that the claimant can and wants to go to trial if settlement fails. In modeling, the capacity and will to proceed to court usually correspond to the fact that the claimant is, somehow, always able to pay for litigation and expects to obtain a positive expected value (PEV) from it. This common assumption is perhaps related to the fact that there is little consensus on how to distinguish socially meritorious lawsuits from those that are frivolous. Although resolving claims with negative expected value (NEV) may be socially valuable, the literature tends not to distinguish NEV cases and frivolous suits.8  Relatively few contributions relax the PEV hypothesis, and Schwartz and Wickelgren (2009) show that the game design strongly affects the possibility of settling NEV cases that will typically remain neither settled nor litigated.9  In a nutshell, the principal interest of the theoretical literature on litigation dynamics seems to be explaining failures of settlement in the shadow of the court—namely, when claimants can at least accomplish a legal remedy through a trial. This approach has generated a rich body of literature on procedural rules and settlement protocols that can influence case selection and hence the settlement rate.10 However, the standard literature seems to place little emphasis on the fact that in the real world many people cannot achieve any legal remedy, because they are unable to be in the shadow of the court.                                                               7 See Bar-Gill (2005), Cooter and Rubinfeld (1994), Gould (1973), Landes (1971), Priest and Klein (1984), and Posner (1973). See Chung (1996) about inconsistent priors. See also Gertner and Miller (1995), who provide a settlement protocol where divergent priors cannot be perfectly communicated and thus remain private information. Starting with P’ng (1983), a strategic approach involving the updating of consistent beliefs has been preferred in analyses of the strategies of rational agents. 8 On the distinction between PEV and NEV cases and meritorious and frivolous cases, see Bebchuk and Chang (1996, p. 372), Katz (1990, p. 3), Nalebuff (1987, FN 3), Polinsky and Rubinfeld (1993, p. 404), Shavell (1982), and Spier (2007). 9 They show that claimants with NEV cases are unable to settle their claims. Conversely, defendants can also resist litigation when they have an NEV defense. Other studies show that NEV claims can be settled in very specific cases: i) in screening models with uninformed defendants (Bebchuk 1988), ii) by making particular assumptions concerning legal costs (Bebchuk 1996, Katz 1990, and Rosemberg and Shavell 1985); and iii) by assuming a claimant’s commitment to proceed, even if his or her updated expected value is negative (Nalebuff 1987). 10 Reviewing this literature is beyond the scope of the current study. Some extensive surveys are available, including those of Daughety and Reinganum (2012), Hay and Spier (2002), and Spier (2007). 5   Besides the theoretical literature, several empirical contributions analyze dispute selection for trial. While theory helps us recognize that the cases that go to trial are filtered by settlement, the empirical literature provides evidence of this phenomenon. However, econometrics offers a very multifaceted picture of the determinants of settlement rate. On the other hand—and probably for data-reliability reasons—the empirical literature on settlement and trial also focuses on cases in the shadow of the court—namely, those that are typically already filed and then legally resolved, by either settlement or trial.11   Finally, the literature on dispute selection for trial apparently does not address the fact that some disputes are not resolved at all, by litigation or by settlement. Since cases where claimants surrender are simply excluded from the analysis, litigation represents a failure because settlement is almost always cheaper (for both the parties involved and for society) and more expeditious than a trial.   2.2. Access to justice The interest in settlement (and in other pre- or extra-judicial solutions) is overriding, especially in developed countries where the primary impression is that the average citizen has too much access to justice.12 In such cases, litigation is perceived as excessive, and the judiciary is costly for taxpayers, the courts are overloaded by an increasing backlog, and consequently the length of proceedings is often too long to be accounted for in the quality of sentencing. For instance, among European Union countries, the average public budget allocated to courts in 2010 was EUR 66 per capita (including public prosecution and legal aid) (CEPEJ 2012). Even though the productivity and efficiency of the courts has improved in some cases, in some countries, the length of proceedings remains impressively protracted. (In Italy, the average duration of a litigious divorce at the first-instance court was 538 days; in Spain, robbery cases have an average duration of 826 days.)13 In 2010, in the United States, the per-capita budget for the judiciary was about USD 22 (without including several items, such as legal aid). In the United States in that year, the problem of heavy caseloads is relevant, as the median of the duration of complex civil proceedings exceeded 687 days.14 Nonetheless, as has been asserted by several institutional contributions to the literature—including the most recent of FRA (2011) and CFCJ (2012)—and by the U.S. Department of Justice (2013), in the most advanced judicial systems, access to justice is critical. The U.S. Department of Justice, in fact, “established the Access to Justice Initiative (ATJ) in March 2010 to address the access-to-justice crisis                                                              11 See Cooter et al. (1982), Hylton and Lin (2010), and Priest and Klein (1984). See also Eisembergh (1990) and Fournier and Zuehlke (1989), each of whom suggest some testable models of settlement and case selection. On the possible determinants of settlement rates and success rates in trials, see Boyd and Hoffman (2012), Farber and White (1991), Gross and Syverud (1991), Huang et al. (2010), and Kessler et al. (1996). 12 See the extensive work of Rhode (2004), and also that of Ramseyer and Rasmusen (2010) and Silver (2002). 13 See CEPEJ (2012); the data refer to first-instance noncriminal courts. 14 Statistics are provided by the Administrative Office of the U.S. Courts on the institutional website. Duration refers to the median time interval in 2010 among civil cases, from filing to trial. 6   in the [American] criminal and civil justice system” (quoted from the ATJ ). Many common people are unable to access the judiciary, often for financial reasons, but there are also other barriers. Some of them decide to seek out unconventional solutions, while others simply give up.15 Despite awareness that access to justice is problematic, information about the extent of the problem, its determinants, and possible solutions remains fragmented. Although financial obstacles do not constitute the sole cause of unmet legal needs, academic contributions have mainly focused on the private costs of litigation.16 Not surprisingly, the most frequently debated of the policies used to address limited access to justice is that pertaining to litigation through legal aid. Recently, new actions like third-party litigation-funding and legal services deregulation have been suggested as ways of making litigation more affordable.17 From a socioeconomic perspective, access to justice has become a fundamental issue, and not only for reasons of fairness.18 Effective access to the judiciary is a leading component of a democratic society.19 Political economics has widely demonstrated—mainly empirically—the positive interdependence of economic and legal institutions. In particular, both adjudication and law enforcement through the courts and well-functioning legal institutions are critical to social and economic growth, since inequalities in terms of rights protections can cause institutional breakdowns and slow growth.20 In general, a lack of access to legal remedies should be a concern not only for those individuals who are unable to pursue their claims; it should be the concern of all citizens, as it affects the health and economic and social well-being of all. The tendency among unresolved disputes (especially in some areas of law) is for there to be an escalation in conflicts, which make resolution more and more difficult. Legal issues such as family matters, injuries from accident and crime, housing and                                                              15 See Coumarelos et al. (2006); Currie (2006), (2009a), and (2009b); Genn (1999); Kritzer (2008); and Rohde (2004). See also the following surveys: AM. BAR ASS’N (1994) and LEGAL SERVS. CORP. (2005) and (2009), with regard to the United States; Genn (1999), with regard to the United Kingdom; and Genn and Paterson (2001), with regard to Scotland. 16 On the obstacles to access to justice, see Genn (1999); Yates et al. (2001); and Kritzer (2008) and (2010). For a development perspective, see UNDP (2004) and (2010) and World Bank (2006). For a theoretical perspective, see also Galanter (2010), Fennel (2010), and Mnookin (1993). On the role of costs, see Buck et al. (2009); Hadfield (2000), (2009), and (2010); and Kritzer (2008) and (2010). 17 See Hodges et al. (2009). On legal aid, see Buchko et al. (2002), Garoupa and Stephen (2004), and Varano and De Luca (2007). Statistics on legal aid in European countries are found in CEPEJ (2012). On third-party litigation funding, see Daffein and Desrieux (2011), Fenn and Rickman (2010), Garber (2010), Molot (2010), and Rodak (2006). On the debate on the market organization of legal services, see Garupa (2013) and Hadfield (2000), (2008), and (2013). 18 Legal scholars have extensively debated the relevance of access to justice as a right that underpins all other rights. See Cappelletti et al. (1979) and Schlesinger (1988), each of whom provide seminal contributions on this topic. See also Alcock (1976), Mattei (2006), and Sommerlad (2004). 19 See Friedman (2006), Marshall (1950), UNDP (2010), and World Bank (2006). 20 See Acemoglu and Johnson (2005), Ellickson (1991), and North (1989). See also Glaeser et al. (2003) and UNDP (2010). 7   employment, fundamental rights like nondiscrimination and health, and disputes with public administrations can exacerbate both social exclusion and overall social costs.21 Scholars have recognized the potential tensions between effective access to justice for all, and the social and private costs related to litigation (Posner 1998; Shavell 1982). However, the theoretical law and economics literature barely works to disentangle the emerging tradeoff between favoring access to justice and curbing expensive litigation. Societies could reduce litigation costs dramatically by discouraging the use of the courts, but if this gives rise to numerous unresolved justiciable problems, its burden on socioeconomic development may be substantial. 3. The Model Given the relevance of the potential tradeoff between litigation and access to justice, the model below addresses the question of dispute resolution, from both private and social perspectives. 3.1. The social planner’s problem From an aggregated perspective, the “social planner’s problem” can be defined as follows. Disputes are assumed to be exogenously determined and can be resolved legally by litigation in court, or by settlement.22 Otherwise, disputes remain unresolved because claimants give up —or, they are resolved by unconventional means, including violence.  Litigation (l) is costly for society. Assume that, on average, resolving a dispute by litigation costs the taxpayers λ. This references the idea that litigation involves a transfer from litigants to the public administration and also that a net negative externality arises.  Alternatively, disputes can be resolved by settlement (s). This system of dispute resolution is assumed not to be costly for society. Otherwise, since settlement is simply less costly than litigation, the social cost of settlement is normalized to zero.  Finally, if disputes remain unresolved or are resolved by unconventional means ( ), the society bears a social cost that relates to the lack of legal solutions. The social cost of includes costs related to reduced social cohesion, diminished security, lower trust, a reduced sense of justice, underdeterrence, social exclusion, morbidity, and violence. On average, an unresolved/unconventionally resolved dispute costs society γ.                                                              21 See Genn (1999); Pleasence et al. (2004), (2006), (2007), and (2008); and Stratton and Anderson (2008). 22 Considerations of endogenous disputes would complicate our analysis, without being overly useful. J J 8   The total number of disputes is normalized to 1, without a loss of generality. Assuming that each “resolution” occurs with a certain probability, the social planner’s problem may correspond to the minimization of the following social loss function: It is evident that the first-best solution for the social planner would be that all disputes be resolved by settlement, with zero social costs. Nonetheless, two main points need to be noted. First of all, even if every dispute were settled (or in general, legally resolved out of court), a court-based system nonetheless needs to be guaranteed. Settlement can exist only as a complement to litigation, since the latter represents the last-resort mechanism in making bargaining agreements enforceable. Conversely, litigation requires no party’s agreement to work, since the winning party achieves an enforceable solution against the other party. Second, by setting procedural rules and the judiciary, the social planner can define the supply for legal solutions (both l and s). Note that in developed legal systems, the supply of legal remedies may be seen as perfectly elastic, at least in the short term. In fact, legal systems do not admit to rationing the supply of legal solutions to justiciable problems. Actually, for a given level of quality or fairness, a less- efficient judiciary can provide legal remedies at a higher cost and with longer delays, while efficient courts can provide solutions at a lower cost and more quickly. However, the social planner cannot directly determine how disputes are actually resolved. This choice in fact rests on how the parties in a conflict decide to resolve their justiciable conflicts. Therefore, to analyze the social planner’s problem, it is necessary to disentangle how the parties work to resolve it. 3.2. The parties’ problem From a micro perspective, the analysis focuses on a representative claimant–defendant pair that is involved in a (monetary) dispute. Both claimant K and defendant Δ are rational and risk-neutral.  The claim amount at stake is A; it is common and public knowledge. This is also the value that is awarded by the court in favor of K, and paid by Δ, if the former prevails in trial because the latter is recognized as liable by the judge. No judicial error can occur over both the magnitude of the claim and the liability of the defendant.  To litigate before the court, K bears a litigation cost CK = cKA, where cK ∈ 0,1 . Actually, rational K never proceeds to trial for cK ≥ 1. If called before the court for trial, Δ must pay a litigation cost equal to CΔ = cΔA, where cΔ ∈ 0,1 . Each party bears his/ her own litigation cost. Litigation costs are public and common knowledge; they include lawyers’ and court fees, taxes, and all the other costs that are privately borne by parties to    Pr Pr 0 Prl s J      9   litigate in court. As commonly assumed in the literature, settlement allows parties to save on litigation costs. The assumption that costs are proportional to the amount at stake is without loss of generality. Furthermore, litigation costs relate largely to the amount at stake rather than, for instance, the actual liability of the defendant (Trubek et al. 1983). In this subsection, no budget constraint restricts the parties’ choices; in subsection 3.4., a budget constraint is introduced for the claimant.  The interaction between the parties is characterized by one-sided asymmetric information concerning the liability of the defendant.23 In particular, K is the uninformed party,  while Δ in the informed party. K does not know if Δ is of a type that will be considered actually liable (type 1) or not (type 0); she only knows that the probability of facing a liable defendant (Δ₁) and prevailing in trial is p, while the probability of facing a nonliable defendant (Δ₀) and losing the case is (1 – p). Δ knows his own type. Note that p can be interpreted as the legal merit of the case. For the sake of simplicity, we assume that the defendant is either fully liable or not liable. This facilitates the interpretation of results, without loss of generality. As explained in subsection 2.1., one- sided asymmetric information models provide a litigation-settlement framework that is sufficiently robust to catch the many insights concerning the parties’ behavior. Since the study focuses on the access-to-justice problem for claimants, the preferred option is to assume that K is the uninformed party. 3.2.1. Access to justice and settlement bargaining Once the dispute arises, if K simply gives up and the dispute remains unresolved, she will not obtain any kind of relief, and both parties will have a null payoff.24 If K expects a positive outcome from litigation, she will access the judiciary and file a case against Δ. However, before the actual trial commences, it is appropriate to attempt a settlement, to avoid litigation costs. Consistent with some of the literature and without any original contribution from the perspective of the settlement process, bargaining is designed as an ultimatum-screening game (Bebchuk 1984; Nalebuff 1987). This allows for understanding several features of trial selection while being functional with regard to the analysis. In particular, the uninformed party—in this case, K—proposes a take-or- leave-it agreement to the informed party—namely, Δ. The take-or-leave-it bid for settlement implies that K commits to going in trial in the case of settlement failure—even if, after bargaining, the expected value of litigation becomes negative.25                                                              23 Saraceno (2008) provides a similar analysis that assumes inconsistent priors. 24 In the case of an unconventional solution, the payoff may differ from zero. However, for the sake of simplicity, this analysis focuses on cases where claimants give up and do not legally proceed. 25 Note that this is consistent with the literature on credible threat and settlement. See, among others, Nalebuff (1987), who investigates both the problem of credible threat and the commitment to go to court of a claimant who has a PEV suit. 10   Therefore, although parties can avoid a trial by settling the case, K wants to access the judiciary to legally resolve the dispute, but only if she has a positive prior on litigation outcome. This explains well the complementarity between litigation and settlement: the latter can be an alternative solution to the former only when litigation is feasible and represents a credible threat. In summary, K accesses justice iff her expected litigation outcome is positive, such that: . (1) When the access to justice condition (1) holds, K can make a credible proposal of settlement to the defendant. She prefers settlement only when she can bargain a settlement amount (S) greater than (or equal to) her expected litigation outcome—thus, when . Obviously, the defendant (Δ) accepts the settlement agreement only if S is smaller than (or equal to) his expected litigation outcome—thus, when: However, the claimant—who naturally wants to maximize her overall payoff—does not know the defendant’s type. Therefore, she faces the usual tradeoff between demanding a high amount that is more easily rejected, and being satisfied with a lower amount that is sure to be accepted. Two equilibrium solutions arise: a pooling strategy equilibrium, and a screening strategy equilibrium. If K demands (pooling strategy), the probability of rejection is null and the case is sure to be settled. Asking for less would be irrational for the claimant. If K demands (screening strategy), the proposal is accepted only by a type-1 defendant (liable)—therefore, with a probability p. Asking for more would be irrational, since the demand would be surely rejected. In the case of a pooling strategy, K obtains a payoff equal to S₀; otherwise, with a screening strategy, she expects to obtain . K’s optimal strategy derives from a comparison of the two possible payoffs. In particular, K opts for a screening strategy when the probability of facing a liable defendant is sufficiently high—that is, when: (2) Two relevant thresholds can be identified with respect to p. The first, the access-to-justice threshold ( ), concerns the possibility K accessing justice. The second, the trial-selection threshold— namely, —concerns the possible legal solutions (i.e. litigation, screening settlement, or pooling settlement) that can be adopted by the parties. ( )Kp c A Kp c ( )KS p c A  0 1 if = (1 ) if = S c A S c A          0S c A 1 (1 )S c A  1 - (1- ) KpS p c A (1 ) K K c c p c c       Kc   1(1 )K Kc c c c     11   In analyzing the thresholds, one must note that the former lies to the left of the latter iff . Therefore, two cases depending on the relative size of the parameters can be distinguished. Case I.  For , no access to justice  For ∆ ∆ , pooling settlement;  For ∆ ∆ , screening settlement with prob. p, litigation with prob. (1-p). Case II.     For , no access to justice  For , screening settlement with prob. p, litigation with prob. (1-p).   The two cases are illustrated in Figure 1. Cases with greater legal merit access justice more frequently than those with lower legal merit. As described in the literature, lower-merit claims accessing the judiciary are settled via pooling settlements (as in case I); those of “intermediate” merit are likely to be litigated, while those of high merit are probably settled via screening settlements. Figure 1. Dispute resolution: parameter thresholds (p). Concerning the parameter restrictions that determine the case I or case II typology, note that ∆ measures the overall litigation costs (for an amount-at-stake unit), while the ratio ∆/ can be interpreted as a measure of economic-power asymmetry between the parties. When parties are symmetric in terms of economic power (i.e., bear the same litigation costs), case I will include cases that are characterized by lower overall litigation ( ). On the other hand, when costs are relatively high ( ), disputes fall into the case II category.  K Kc c c c     12 1K K K K c c c c c c c          12 1K K K K c c c c c c c        Kc c 1 2  Kc c 1 2  12   For a given level of total litigation costs, case I corresponds to a relatively more powerful claimant who can litigate by paying a low share of the overall costs. Conversely, case II corresponds to a more powerful defendant who is able to stay in trial by paying a lower share of overall litigation costs. Figure 2 shows how the two cases are determined, for different litigation cost levels.26 Appendix A.1. further discusses how changes in the parameters shift the analysis from case I to case II, and vice versa. Figure 2. Litigation costs and analytical cases 3.2.2. Rates of access to justice, settlement, and litigation: Comparative statics The analysis below illustrates how changes in the relevant parameters affect litigation and access to justice for an overall unitary amount of disputes emerging within a society. The following exercise in comparative statics is carried out while assuming that each claimant–defendant pair has a dispute characterized by a certain legal merit p i.i.d. as a standard uniform distribution: 27 We define a number of measures that are relevant to policy implications:  J is the rate of access to justice. This is a measure of demand for legal remedies. Its complement to 1 measures the rate of disputes remaining unresolved (or unconventionally resolved).  l, s0, and s1 are the absolute rates of litigation, pooling settlement, and screening settlement, respectively. They naturally sum to J. As seen previously, two cases must be distinguished in line with the parameter restrictions. Table 1 provides the absolute rates for the two cases. All rates can be easily rewritten as a function of A. In addition, since the literature usually analyzes litigation and settlement rates by focusing on claims in the shadow of the court—namely, those that can actually access the judiciary—we define:  l/J and s/J as the standardized rates of litigation and settlement, respectively. They naturally sum to 1. Standardized rates can be calculated simply by dividing the corresponding absolute rates by J.                                                              26 The red curve corresponding to equation represents the frontier along which the two thresholds overlap perfectly. Along the 45-degree line, the costs are symmetric. 27 The use of the uniform distribution allows us to obtain very tractable results. For other symmetric probability distributions of p, the uniform distribution provides robust insights. Asymmetric distributions complicate the analysis without substantially jeopardizing general results.  0,1 .p u   12 1K Kc c c    13   Table 1. Absolute rates of access to justice, settlement, and litigation Case I.  Case II.  Tables 2 and 3 summarize the signs of the partial derivatives of the rates with respect to the model parameters. Uncertain signs are discussed in the text, as their analysis offers useful insights. Details are provided in Appendix A.2. Results of the comparative statics both support a number of Propositions (1– 4) and allow us to discuss a number of policies. Case I Regarding access to justice, it is easy to understand that access to justice positively depends on the amount at stake, while depending negatively on the claimant’s litigation costs. Given the allocation of litigation costs, the defendant costs do not influence access to justice. Comparative statics on the defendant’s litigation costs provides standard and intuitive results: high costs discourage (screening) settlement against litigation, in both absolute and standardized terms. Table 2. Case I: Effects of parameter changes on absolute and standardized rates A J - 0 + s0 - + - if s1 - - + s - + - if l - - + s /J + if + - if l /J - if - + if is the elasticity of J with respect to . Analysis of the claimant costs and the amount at stake shows less-than-standard but fairly sound insights. Increasing the claimant costs reduces both settlement (pooling and screening) and litigation   12 1K Kc c c      12 1K Kc c c            1 1 0 1 1 2 1 0 1 2 1 2 1 1 1 1 2 1 1 1 2 1 1 1 2 1 K K K K K K K K Kc c c Kc c Kc K K c c K c c K K K c c c c K J dp c c c s dp c c c c c s pdp c c c s s s c c c l p dp c c                                                           1 0 1 2 1 1 2 1 0 1 1 2 1 1 1 2 K K K Kc Kc Kc J dp c s s s pdp c l p dp c                Kc c  , 1 KJ c K c     , 1 KJ c K c     , 1 KJ c K c     , 1 KJ c     , 1 KJ c K c     , 1 KJ c    , K K J c K cJ c J     Kc 14   because then fewer claims can access justice. Increasing the amount at stake unambiguously increases both screening settlement and litigation; in fact, in such cases, more claims can access justice, and those characterized by a higher probability of success are settled for a screening amount. Litigation increases through two drivers: augmented access to justice, and a partial shift of some claims from pooling settlement to litigation. The remaining effects are ambiguous. Only under some parameter restrictions are the effects as expected. To discuss these restrictions, we also resort to the (absolute value of the) elasticity of the demand for legal remedies . This is a monotonically increasing function of , defined over the interval . Concerning the effects of changes in on the standardized rate of litigation (settlement), it is evident that increasing the claimant cost reduces both the proportion of disputes that go to trial and the proportion of disputes that can access justice. This combined action can increase or decrease the standardized rate of litigation (settlement). The standardized rates of litigation and settlement behave as usual—namely, the former decreases, while the latter increases by the same amount in —only when corresponding to , 1 ˆ( ) ( ) 1, , 2K J c K K c c c c c c            (details in Appendix A.2). Figure 3 (left) illustrates the parameter restriction in terms of costs. The dashed dark line in the graph represents the elasticity , ( )KJ c Kc , which can be measured along the y-axis. Figure 3. Effects of changes in on the standardized rates of litigation and settlement: Case I Figure 3 (right) shows the parameter restriction in terms of elasticity. In particular, the increasing curve represents the elasticity of the demand for legal remedies, along the frontier between case I and   1, 1K K J c K K K cJ c c c J       Kc  0,  Kc Kc 1 3c c   Kc 15   case II; it is also the upper limit of the elasticity for case I.28 The decreasing curve corresponds to the threshold ˆ( )c  , which is always (significantly) smaller than 1. The standardized rate of litigation (settlement) decreases (increases) with an increase in the claimant’s litigation cost, as usually described in the literature—but only if the demand for legal remedies is sufficiently inelastic (light-grey areas in both figures). It is evident that when , ( ) 1KJ c Kc  , the effect of reduced access to justice prevails, and the standardized rate of litigation increases (settlement decreases). Increasing the amount at stake ambiguously affects both the absolute rate of pooling settlement and the absolute rate of total settlement. In fact, a higher amount at stake both favors access to justice and shifts some claims from pooling to screening settlement and litigation. This happens because the claimant is asking for more to settle. On the other hand, a larger amount at stake spurs the defendant to settle. The combined effects can increase or decrease the absolute rates of pooling and total settlement. The absolute rate of pooling settlement decreases in A under the following parameter restriction: . The parameter restriction to have an absolute rate of settlement decreasing in A is stricter: . Analysis of these restrictions is not straightforward; details are discussed in Appendix A.2. These parameter restrictions on parties’ costs correspond to the elasticity threshold ˆ̂( ) 1 ,Kc c c    ; this implies that an increase in the amount at stake reduces the rate of pooling settlement only when a claimant’s litigation cost is sufficiently low—or, in other words, when the demand for legal remedies is inelastic. Therefore, when the demand is elastic (or there is unitary elasticity), an increase in the amount at stake enlarges the rate of pooling settlement. Note that the second parameter restriction is more binding than the first one; we can conclude that, when the demand for legal remedies is elastic (or there is unitary elasticity), the absolute rate of settlement is increasing in A. The intuition is clear: when the demand for legal remedies is elastic, the effect of augmented access to justice owing to a greater amount at stake prevails on the partial shifting from settlement to litigation. Concerning the standardized rate of litigation, note that a higher amount at stake enlarges both the proportion of disputes that go in trial and the proportion of disputes that access justice. This combined action can increase or decrease the standardized rate of litigation. The latter increases in only when . In terms of elasticity, this restriction corresponds to  2, 1 18 9 1 1 ( ) 1 2 4K J c c c c c c                (details in Appendix A.2.). Figure 4 (left) illustrates the parameter restriction in terms of costs. As usual, the dashed dark line in the graph                                                              28 Elasticity along the frontier has the equation . 2 K K Kc <(c +c )(1+c +c )    3 K K Kc <(c +c )(1+c +c )    A      1> 3 1 1- 3 1K K Kc c c c       0.5 0.5 4c c c      16   represents , ( )KJ c Kc , which can be measured along the y-axis. Figure 4 (right) shows the parameter restriction in terms of elasticity. Figure 4. Effects of changes in on the standardized rates of litigation and settlement: Case I The thinner line corresponds to the threshold . The standardized rate of litigation (settlement) is increasing (decreasing) in the amount at stake, only if the elasticity of the demand for legal remedies is sufficiently low (light grey areas in both figures). In particular, for case I, when , ( ) 1KJ c Kc  , then , ( ) ( ), ,KJ c K Kc c c c     . Therefore, when the demand for legal remedies is inelastic, the standardized rate of litigation (settlement) is increasing (decreasing) in A. When the elasticity is high and the defendant cost is sufficiently large (therefore, for values that are close to the frontier and between case I and case II), the standardized rate of settlement can be decreasing in A. The insight is intuitive: when the defendant incurs a high cost to stay in trial, he has a strong incentive to settle. Therefore, the augmented access to justice stemming from a higher amount at stake results in more settlement and less litigation. Case II Analysis concerning case II is simpler, since the effects of parameter changes on the relevant rates are unambiguous. As usual, low claimant costs and a high amount at stake increase access to justice. Table 3. Effects of parameter changes on absolute and standardized rates: Case II A J - 0 + s=s1 - 0 + l - 0 + s /J + 0 - l /J - 0 + A  Kc c 17   Nonetheless, even in this case, some of the current results depart from those in the standard literature. In particular, it is evident that defendant costs do not affect both absolute and standardized rates. Conversely, as in the standard literature, higher claimant costs and a lower amount at stake favor settlement against litigation for claims in the shadow of the court (standardized rates). On the other hand, higher claimant costs and a lower amount at stake discourage both settlement and litigation. 3.2.3. Propositions and remarks Given the results of the analysis in the previous subsection, it is possible to summarize the most relevant results through a number of propositions. Proposition 1. Claims characterized by a higher legal merit can access the judiciary more easily. The rate of access to justice is decreasing in the claimant cost and increasing in the amount at stake. It is not influenced by the defendant cost. Proposition 2. The absolute rate of litigation is decreasing in the claimant cost, increasing in the amount at stake, and negatively or not at all affected by the defendant cost (case I and case II, respectively). Propositions 1 and 2 illustrate the potential tradeoff between favoring access to justice and discouraging litigation through the enactment of policies, resulting in larger litigation costs among claimants. Furthermore, even if able to encourage access to justice, procedures that inflate the amount at stake of lawsuits must be carefully appraised, since they ultimately promote litigation. However, the aforementioned propositions also show that the tradeoff does not necessarily emerge. In particular, and different from the standard literature, the model used herein shows that the parties’ costs asymmetrically affect dispute selection for trial. First, higher defendant costs do not discourage access to justice, even as they potentially curtail litigation. In particular, larger defendant costs will reduce the litigation rate, provided the defendant is “sufficiently exposed” to the costs of going to trial (case I). On the other hand, when the defendant bears litigation costs that are low relative to the overall litigation costs (case II), marginal enlargements in his costs will not affect the litigation rates, since the rate of access to justice will remain the same and the selection of claims between (screening) settlement and trial will be driven only by the probability of claimant success. Proposition 3. Given (case I), the standardized rate of litigation (settlement) is decreasing (increasing) in the claimant cost and increasing (decreasing) in the amount at stake, only if the demand for legal remedies is sufficiently inelastic. The standardized rate of litigation (settlement) is always decreasing (increasing) in the defendant cost.   12 1K Kc c c    18   Given   (case II), the standardized rate of litigation (settlement) is decreasing in the claimant cost, increasing in the amount at stake, and not affected by the defendant cost. Proposition 3 shows that reductions in litigation costs and/or increases in the amount at stake do not necessarily promote the standardized rate of litigation. These results—which extend beyond those usually seen in the standard literature—are driven by the fact that here we take into account both litigation and access to justice. In particular, case I illustrates that the elasticity of the demand for legal remedies plays a key role in determining the effects of changes in parties’ costs and the benefit of trial on the standardized rate of litigation (settlement). Finally, policymakers with an interest in addressing the double issue of favoring access to justice while discouraging litigation should put additional effort into investigating the elasticity of the demand for legal remedies in different systems and for different legal matters. 3.3. Revising the social problem Given the model of the parties’ behavior presented in the previous subsection, we return to the social problem. Recalling that the overall amount of disputes emerging within society is standardized to 1, the representative dispute is assumed to be characterized as that between Δ and K. Note that parties’ private litigation costs are transfers (in favor of their lawyers, to pay litigation fees, etc.), but that from a social perspective, the average net externality stemming from the resolution of a dispute by litigation is λ. If the dispute is not legally resolved, society bears a net negative externality γ. Now, the social loss function (1) needs to be rewritten as: (3) It is straightforward that, for a given rate of access to justice, policies that are able to reduce the absolute litigation rate can unambiguously moderate the social costs of dispute resolution. More caution is required with policies that affect both rates. 3.3.1. Socially meritorious claims Recalling that and distinguishing between cases I and II, (3) can be rewritten as: .   12 1K Kc c c     1 Jl     1 KJ c        2 2 1 in Case I 1 in 1 2 2 Case I 1 I 2 J c J J J                19   In both cases, the first term of the sum represents the social cost of dispute resolution owing to litigation, while the second term is the social cost owing to the lack of legal resolution for justiciable problems. Since the first term is increasing in J and the second one is decreasing, favoring access to justice involves a tradeoff because of the increase in litigation. A simple condition is necessary (and sufficient) to having the social costs of dispute resolution decrease in J for both cases (see Appendix A.3.): (4) This condition provides some insights that are valuable from a policy perspective. First, when the social cost stemming from a lack of legal remedies is greater than or even equal to that borne by society for litigation, improving access to justice moderates the social costs of dispute resolution (note that is always smaller than 1). The intuition is simple: since not every justiciable problem shifted from the sample of those unresolved to the sample of those accessing the judiciary is resolved through litigation, improving access to justice unambiguously reduces the social cost of dispute resolution. Thanks to settlement, this is true even when the social cost stemming from a lack of legal remedies is equal to the social cost of litigation. Condition (4) also suggests that, in the debate on the concept of meritorious claims, it would be useful to distinguish between socially meritorious claims and privately meritorious claims. Socially meritorious claims can be identified as those disputes that are characterized by the claimants’ marginal propensity to litigate being smaller than the social opportunity-cost of access to justice ( ). Privately meritorious claims continue to be identifiable as those characterized by a PEV ( ). Naturally, the two concepts do not necessarily overlap. 3.3.2. Propositions and policy analysis Given the aforementioned analysis, it is possible to summarize the most relevant results of the model with respect to the social perspective, through a number of propositions and policy remarks. Proposition 4. Discouraging litigation without affecting access to justice is socially efficient. Note that this statement specifically concerns PEV lawsuits that are in the shadow of the court, since they can be actually litigated in the event of settlement failure. Proposition 5. Favoring access to justice always increases litigation; this can result in ambiguous social effects. It is always efficient to improve access to justice for socially meritorious claims, which are defined as those claims characterized by the claimant’s marginal propensity to litigate being 0 iff K l J c         Kl c     Kp c 20   smaller than the social opportunity-cost of access to justice. At least, this implies that it is always efficient to improve access to justice when the social cost stemming from a lack of legal remedies is greater than or even equal to the cost of litigation.   By combining the results of this subsection with those derived in the previous one, one can draw some policy implications. In particular, making litigation expensive for parties by charging claimants high litigation fees ambiguously affects the social cost of dispute resolution. Since this kind of policy discourages both litigation and access to justice, it exacerbates the tradeoff between the two policy goals. This sort of intervention could be useful only in a context of legal matters that involve very low social costs owing to a lack of resolutions and relatively high litigation costs. Conversely, higher litigation fees charged to defendants may reduce the expected social cost of dispute resolution by discouraging litigation, but while not affecting access to justice. However, this policy would also come with some limitations. The first limitation is of procedural fairness: it could be unfair to impose particularly high litigation costs on a defendant, who has in fact been forced into the process of defending him or herself. Discussions of fairness, however, extend beyond the present analysis. The second limitation stems from the fact that making litigation more expensive for defendants is ineffective when a pooling settlement is not feasible (case II). On the other hand, significant increases in defendant costs can make a pooling settlement feasible, finally resulting in less litigation. (On the shift from case II to case I, see Appendix A.1.) Concerning policies that affect the amount at stake, we mention only punitive damages and forms of civil or additional penalties. Punitive damages are paid by the defendant in favor of the winning claimant, with the aim of acting as a deterrent. They can be seen as an increase in A (perhaps they are also able to reduce γ). Punitive damages ambiguously affect the expected social costs of dispute resolution, given the usual tradeoff between the augmented rate of access to justice and the rising absolute rate of litigation. From a social perspective, such policies should be implemented only for socially meritorious claims. Penalties that are paid to the state—like civil or additional penalties—typically increase the amount at stake only for the defendant, without affecting the claimant’s amount at stake. They can be seen as an additional litigation cost paid by the defendant, but only in the case of the claimant’s success. They can discourage litigation without influencing access to justice. In addition, they might also be beneficial in terms of improved deterrence, perhaps reducing γ. 3.4. Claimants under budget constraints The above analysis completely ignores the possibility that the parties cannot pay their litigation costs. Since this study focuses on access-to-justice issues, the analysis below introduces a budget constraint for the claimant. On the other hand, the defendant continues to be assumed always solvent 21   (e.g., a large and professional defendant, or someone covered by insurance), and we choose not to consider “judgment proof” problems.29 Define ∈(0,∞) as K’s wealth normalized by A. In such a case, condition (1) is not enough to guarantee access to justice. An additional condition must be verified: the claimant’s wealth must be sufficient to cover the litigation cost ( ). No information asymmetry exists between the parties concerning their wealth.30 In summary, under the claimant’s budget constraint, the condition to access justice is: (5) Assume that normalized wealth among the population of potential claimants is a random variable distributed according to the density function h, with cumulative function H and independent of p. Note that the probability that the claimant is able to cover her litigation costs is , which is monotonically decreasing in and, recalling that , monotonically increasing in A. The rate of access to justice under a budget constraint— —is always smaller than that lacking a budget constraint. It is trivial to note that for a given probability of success, an unconstrained population of claimants can more readily access justice than a constrained one. Additionally, the absolute rate of litigation under a budget constraint— in case I and in case II—is always smaller than that without a budget constraint. On the other hand, the standardized rates of litigation (settlement) with or without a budget constraint are the same. These findings can be summarized by the following proposition. Proposition 6. The standardized rate of litigation (settlement) is not affected by the fact that the access to justice of some claimants is hampered by their budget constraints. Conversely, both the absolute rate of litigation and the rate of access to justice are smaller when there is a budget constraint for claimants.                                                              29 A judgment proof problem occurs when a defendant does not pay the appropriate damage award—for instance, because he or she goes bankrupt. See, for instance, Shavell (1986) and Summer (1983). 30 The capacity of the claimant to pay for litigation costs is obviously a further element that plays a role in the credibility of the threat to go to trial. Relaxing the hypothesis that the defendant knows the wealth of the claimant complicates the dynamics of settlement bargaining, without adding any insight useful to the aims of this study. Moreover, it seems sound to assume that the defendant can infer or even know the claimant’s wealth since in the real world, for instance, relations between parties are mediated by legal firms and lawyers that work as (costly) signals of claimant wealth. w Kw c K K p c w c    Pr( ) 1 ( )K Kw c H c   Kc K Kc C A     1 1K Kc H c      212 1 1K Kc c H c          212 1 1 K K c H c   22   Again, analysis of the absolute rates highlights the potential tradeoff between litigation and access to justice: less-stringent budget constraints result in more access to justice, but also in more litigation. On the other hand, since we consider exogenous litigation costs, once in the shadow of the court, “poorer” claimants are no different from “richer” ones, in terms of litigation rate. 3.5. Social tradeoff and legal aid Given the model of the parties’ behavior with budget constraints, the social loss function becomes: . (6) The social cost of dispute resolution when claimants’ behavior is restricted by budget constraints (6) is not necessarily larger than that lacking budget constraints (3). Actually, under budget constraints, there is less litigation—but also, fewer disputes are legally resolved. However, in comparing (3) and (6), it is easy to see that if (6.1.). This condition bears several implications. First, since the standardized rate of litigation is always smaller than 1, when the social cost stemming from a lack of legal remedies is greater than or even equal to the social cost of litigation, the inability of a part of the population to access the judiciary (owing to budget constraints) relates not only to a fairness problem but also to a degradation of social conditions because the social costs of dispute resolution are higher. This suggests that reforms and policies that aim to improve access to justice should focus on legal matters that when unresolved relate to high social costs (i.e., family law matters). From this perspective, legal aid as a form of litigation subsidization is an important issue. Legal aid is the main policy tool to arise in discussions concerning the issue of access to justice. Legal aid—as the provision of assistance to people who are otherwise unable to afford legal representation and access the court system—is specifically regulated in each country, and can differ widely in terms of coverage, amounts, and delivery models. Here, legal aid is assumed to take the form of a state fund that covers litigation costs for claimants who would otherwise be unable to access the judiciary. We choose not to consider potential abuses or moral hazard (i.e., legal aid does not determine any enrichment for recipients). In the case of a claimant’s success in trial, the legal aid amount is returned to the state. Thus, legal aid allows all claimants with insufficient wealth to proceed with their PEV claims. According to the above analysis, since we assume that legal aid is simply a transfer from the state to “poor” claimants, subsidizing litigation is socially efficient as long as the social opportunity-cost of access to justice is greater than the standardized rate of litigation. In particular, we can verify that it is socially efficient in subsidizing both all the socially meritorious claims falling into the case II category, and those included in case I that are characterized by a sufficiently inelastic demand for legal remedies ( ).      . . 1 ( ) 1 1 ( ) ( ) b c K K K H c J H cl H c          . .b c    l J    , KJ c   23   It can remain efficient in subsidizing socially meritorious claims that fall into the case I category, inasmuch as they are characterized by a higher elasticity of demand for legal remedies ( and as long as the standardized rate of litigation remains smaller than the social opportunity-cost of access to justice. (Proofs are provided in Appendix A.4.) Usually, however, legal aid is not a simple transfer; it is also costly for taxpayers. Below, the assumption of legal aid being a pure transfer is relaxed by assuming that legal aid is a net negative externality for taxpayers. The overall cost of legal aid for society is , since the cost of legal aid is equal to the claimant’s litigation cost, weighted by the probability of being “poor” and “losing in trial.” Therefore, the social cost of dispute resolution by using legal aid becomes: (7) It is straightforward to verify that for (7.1.). Condition (7.1.) is obviously stricter than condition (6.1.). Intuitively, when legal aid is socially costly, subsidizing litigation is efficient under a condition that is stricter than when legal aid is a simple transfer. However, condition (7.1.) can be easily interpreted, and it provides further insights. For a given standardized rate of litigation (which is always smaller than 1), it is efficient to remove financial obstacles to access to justice by providing socially costly legal aid, as long as the standardized rate of litigation remains smaller than the overall opportunity cost of access to justice (defined as the ratio of γ to the sum of both social and private litigation costs per dispute). Note that the left term of the inequality (7.1.) is increasing in p and decreasing in . Since claims that are characterized by a higher p both access justice more frequently and are litigated less frequently, condition (7.1.) is more easily satisfied for high-merit legal claims. A comparison of (6.1.) and (7.1.) shows that room for the socially efficient subsidization of litigation is reduced when legal aid is socially costly. However, improving access to justice through partial subsidization continues to be a suitable policy, especially if legal aid systems are able to select claims in terms of legal merit. This suggests that a suitable criterion by which to select the claims to be subsidized should work as a sort of legal-merit filter. Concerning litigation costs, note that lower costs do not necessarily satisfy (7.1.) easily, since the standardized rate of litigation can be either increasing or decreasing in (see subsection 3.2.). Therefore, once again, policies that affect claimant costs should be carefully evaluated. The following proposition summarizes the main insights of this subsection.  , )KJ c  ( ) (1- )K KH c l p c = ( ) (1- ) (1- )aid K Kl H c l p c J    . . >b c aid  >(1- ) K l p c J    Kc Kc 24   Proposition 7. When legal aid is a transfer, it is socially efficient in subsidizing socially meritorious claims that fall into case II, or those falling into case I that are characterized by a sufficiently inelastic demand for legal remedies. Socially meritorious claims falling into case I but characterized by a high elasticity of demand for legal remedies must be subsidized as long as the standardized rate of litigation is sufficiently low. When legal aid is a net externality for society, efficient subsidization is lower, but still positive. In general, it is socially efficient to subsidize litigation, as long as the standardized rate of litigation is lower than the social opportunity-costs of access to justice. Proposition 7 and the analysis provided in subsection 3.2. together suggest that some policies may be socially effective at best, and seriously detrimental at worst. For instance, for claims characterized by a very inelastic demand for legal remedies (i.e., falling into case I, with ), legal aid and increasing litigation costs for claimants represent a policy mix with serious adverse effects, as it would become more difficult to satisfy condition 7.1. Another possible example concerns claims that fall into case I: legal aid could be socially beneficial when defendants’ litigation costs are particularly high, since the right term of condition (7.1.) is decreasing in , even as the left term remains unaffected. Finally, any assessment of policies that influence the judiciary should be based on a careful appraisal of both their effects on the social opportunity-cost of access to justice and their influence on private parties’ behavior. Several policies determine the nature of complex interactions between litigation and access to justice; these interactions deserve particular attention, if unexpected and adverse social results are to be precluded. 4. Conclusions The dynamics of settlement and litigation in the shadow of the court have been discussed extensively by law and economics scholars. Although it is beneficial in terms of deterrence and reducing legal uncertainty by defining legal precedent, litigation is usually perceived as socially wasteful. This is certainly true if the alternative to litigation is another legal solution like settlement. However, if the alternative to litigation is that claimants fail to find any legal remedy to their justiciable problems—or even try to resolve their conflicts by unconventional means—then litigation may represent for society a suitable second-best option. This study investigates the social tradeoff that emerges between litigation and access to justice. While considering access to justice, the results of the current model lead one to question some of the standard insights of the law and economics literature on litigation and settlement rates. In particular, the results indicate that high litigation costs on the part of the claimant discourage both settlement and litigation, that high values at stake ambiguously affect settlement, and that defendant costs possibly have no role in determining the type of legal solution selected by parties. Finally, the effects of changes , KJ c    c 25   in costs and amounts at stake on the rates of settlement and litigation for claims in the shadow of the court depend upon the elasticity of the demand for legal remedies. The framework that derives from the model helps to clarify the effects of a number of policies, in terms of both litigation and access to justice. Policies that affect claimant behavior—such as those pertaining to litigation fees and punitive damages—often exacerbate the social tradeoff between litigation and access to justice. Policies that increase defendant costs—like high defense fees or additional penalties—can either reduce litigation without hampering access to justice, or be completely ineffective. Although improving access to justice will necessarily promote litigation, favoring full and effective access to the judiciary can be socially efficient. On this basis, the current study suggests the use of a new criterion by which to define and filter claims as socially meritorious. Socially meritorious claims are those where a claimant’s marginal propensity to litigate is smaller than the social opportunity-cost of access to justice. Guaranteeing access to justice of socially meritorious claims, even at the cost of promoting litigation, is always efficient. The current study also analyzed the social tradeoff between litigation and access to justice when claimants are hampered in their access to the judiciary because of budget constraints. Both the absolute rate of litigation and the rate of access to justice are smaller when some claimants are limited by their under budget constraints. From a social perspective, it is efficient to remove budget constraints by subsidizing litigation, as long as the standardized rate of litigation is lower than the social opportunity- costs of access to justice. In conclusion, although the model presented in this study simplifies assumptions within a setting that involves standard take-it-or-leave-it screening settlement bargaining, it provides a rather general framework. According to this framework, policymakers with an interest in reducing the social costs of dispute resolution should acquire a profound understanding of how policies influence both the rate of access to justice and the absolute and standardized rates of litigation. The same solution could be socially helpful in certain kinds of claims while being socially detrimental in other kinds of cases. In particular, the social opportunity-cost of access to justice, the claimants’ marginal propensity to litigate, and the elasticity of the demand for legal remedies become factors that allow us to determine the success or failure of a given policy.    26   References Acemoglu, D. and S. Johnson (2005). Unbundling institutions. 113, Journal of Political Economy, 949. AM. BAR ASS’N (1994), Legal Needs and Civil Justice: A Survey of Americans, Major Findings from the Comprehensive Legal Needs Study. www.abanet.org/legalservices/downloads/sclaid/legalneedstudy.pdf. Alcock P.C. (1976). Legal Aid: Whose Problem? 3, British Journal of Law and Society, 151-178. Bar-Gill, O. (2005). The Evolution and Persistence of Optimism in Litigation. 22, Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization 490-507. Bebchuk, L.A. (1984). Litigation and Settlement under Imperfect Information. 15, RAND Journal of Economics, 404- 415. (1988). Suing Solely to Extract a Settlement Offer. 17, Journal of Legal Studies, 437-450. (1996). A New Theory Concerning the Credibility of Success of Threats to Sue. 25, Journal of Legal Studies, 1-26. Bebchuk, L.A. and H.F. Chang. (1996) An Analysis of Fee Shifting Based on the Margin of Victory: On Frivolous Suits, Meritorious Suits, and the Role of Rule 11. 25 Journal of Legal Studies, 371-404. Boyd, C.L. and D.A. Hoffman. (2012). Litigating Toward Settlement. 3, Journal of Law, Economics, & Organization, 2-52. Buchko, K.A., Rekosh, E., and V. Terziev. (2002). “Access to Justice: Legal Aid for the Underrepresented” In Buchko, K.A., Rekosh, E., and V. Terzieva, (Eds.) Pursuing the Public Interest: A Handbook for Legal Professionals and Activists. New York: Columbia Law School. Buck, A., Day, L., Collard, S., Smith, M., and A. Patel. (2009). Outreach advice for debt problems: Research and evaluation of outreach services for financially excluded people. Legal Services Commission. Cappelletti, M., Garth, B., Weisner, J., and K.F. Koch. (1979). Access to Justice. HeinOnline. CEPEJ. (2012). European Judicial Systems. CEPEJ’s Studies No. 18. Council of Europe Publishing. CFCJ. (2012). The Cost of Justice. Weighing the Costs of fair and Effective Resolution to Legal Problems. The Canadian Forum on Civil Justice. Che, Y.K. and J. G. YI. (1993). The Role of Precedents in Repeated Litigation. 9, Journal of Law, Economics and Organization, 399-424. Chung, T.Y, (1996). Settlement of Litigation under Rule 68: An Economic Analysis. 25, Journal of Legal Studies, 261-286. Cooter, R.D., Marks, S., and R. Mookin. (1982). Bargaining in the Shadow of the Law: A Testable Model of Strategic Behavior. 11, Journal of Legal Studies, 225-251. Cooter, R.D. and D.L. Rubinfeld. (1989). Economic Analysis of Legal Disputes and Their Resolution. XVII, Journal of Economics Literature, 1067-1097. (1994). An Economic Model of Legal Discovery. 23, Journal of Legal Studies, 435-463. Coumarelos, C., Wei, Z. and A.Z. Zhou. (2006). Justice made to measure: NSW legal needs survey in disadvantaged areas. Access to justice and legal needs, vol. 3, Law and Justice Foundation of NSW, Sydney. Currie, A. (2006). A national survey of the civil justice problems of low and moderate income Canadians: Incidence and patterns. 13, International Journal of the Legal Profession, 217-242. (2009a). The legal problems of everyday life. In R.L. Sandefur (Ed.), Sociology of Crime, Law and Deviance, Vol. 12, 1-41. Bingley, UK: Emerald. 27   (2009b). A lightning rod for discontent: Justiciable problems and attitudes towards the law and the justice system. In A. Buck, P. Pleasence, and N.J. Balmer (Eds.), Reaching further: Innovation, access and quality in legal services, 100-114. Legal Services Research Centre. UK: The Stationery Office. Dari-Mattiacci, G. and B. Deffains. (2007). Uncertainty of Law and the Legal Process. 163, Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 627-656. Daughety, A.F. and J.F. Reinganum. (1993). Endogenous Sequencing in Models of Settlement and Litigation. 9, Journal of Law, Economics and Organization; 314-48. (1994). Settlement Negotiations with Two Sided Asymmetric Information: Model Duality, Information Distribution, and Efficiency. 14, International Review of Law and Economics, 283-98 (2012). “Settlement” in C.W. Sanchirico (Ed.) Procedural Law and Economics, Vol. 8 Ch. 15, The Encyclopedia of Law and Economics (Second Ed.), Edward Elgar Publishing Ltd. Deffains, B. and C. Desrieux. (2011).Financing Litigation: A Comparative Analysis,” Working Paper, University of Paris II. Eisenberg, T. (1990). Testing the Selection Effect: A New Theoretical Framework with Empirical Tests. 19, Journal of Legal Studies, 337-358. Ellickson, R.C. (1991) Order without law: How neighbours settle disputes. Harvard Univ. Press Farber, H.S. and M.J. White. (1991). Medical malpractice: An Empirical Examination of the Litigation Process. 22, RAND Journal of Economics, 199-217. Fenn, P. and N. Rickman. (2010) The empirical analysis of litigation funding. In M. Tuill and L. Visscher (Eds.) New Trends in Financing Civil Litigation in Europe: A Legal, Empirical, and Economic Analysis. 131-148. Edward Elgar Publishing. Fennell M.A. Using State Legal Needs Studies to Increase Access to Justice for Low-Income Families. 48, Family Court Review, 619-630. Fournier, G.M. and T.W. Zuehlke. (1996). The Timing of Out-of-Court Settlements. 27, RAND Journal of Economics, 310-321. FRA (2011). Access to justice in Europe: An overview of challenges and opportunities European. Union Agency for Fundamental Rights, Publications Office of the European Union. Friedman, B. (2006). Taking law seriously. 4, Perspectives on Politics, 261-276. Friedman, D. and D. Wittman. (2006). Litigation with Symmetric Bargaining and Two-Sided Incomplete Information. 23, Journal of Law, Economics, and Organization, 98-126. Galanter, M. (1983). The Radiating Effects of Courts. 117, Empirical theories about courts, 117-142. (2010) Access to Justice in a World of Expanding Social Capability. 37, Fordham Urban Law Journal, 115-128. Garber, S. (2010). Alternative Litigation Financing in the United States. RAND Institute for Civil - Justice Law, Finance, and Capital Markets Program, Occasional Paper, 2010 Garoupa, N. (2013). Globalization and Deregulation of Legal Services. Mimeo. Garoupa, N., and F.H. Stephen. (2004). Optimal Law Enforcement with Legal Aid. 71, Economica 493- 500. Genn, H. (1999). Paths to justice: What people think about going to law. Oxford: Hart Publishing. Genn, H. and A. Paterson. (2001). Paths to justice Scotland: What people in Scotland do and think about going to law. Portland, OR: Hart Publishing. Gertner, R.H. and G.P. Miller. (1995). Settlement Escrows. 24, Journal of Legal Studies, 87-122. 28   Glaeser, E., Scheinkman, J. and A. Shleifer. (2003) The injustice of inequality. 50, Journal Monetary Economics, 199-222. Gould, J.P. (1973). The Economics of Legal Conflicts. 2, Journal of Legal Studies, 279-300. Gross, S.R. and K.D. Syverud. (1991). Getting to No: A study of Settlement Negotiations and the Selection of Cases for Trial. 90 Michigan Law Review, .319-393. Hadfield G.K. (2000) The Price of Law: How the Market for Lawyers Distorts the Justice System. 98, Michigan Law Review, 953-1006. (2008). The levers of legal design: Institutional determinants of the quality of law. 36, Journal of Comparative Economics, 43–73. (2010). Higher Demand, Lower Supply? A Comparative Assessment of the Legal Resource Landscape for Ordinary Americans. 37, Fordham Urban Law Journal, 129-150. (2013). The Cost of Law: Promoting Access to Justice through the Corporate Practice of Law. Bepress. Hay, B.L. and K.E. Spier. (1998). “Settlement of Litigation” in P. Newman (Ed.), The New Palgrave Dictionary of Law and Economics, Macmillan Reference Limited, Vol. 3, 442-451. Hylton, K.N. and H. Lin. (2010). Trial Selection Theory: A Unified Model. BU School of Law Working Paper, 10-12. Hodges, C., Vogenauer, S., and M. Tulibacka. (2009). Costs and funding of civil litigation: A comparative study. Oxford Legal Research Paper Series, Paper No 55/2009. Huang, K.C., Chen, K.P., and C.C. Lin. (2010). An Empirical Investigation of Settlement and Litigation - The Case of Taiwanese Labor Disputes. 7, Journal of Empirical Legal Studies, 786–810. Katz, A. (1990). The Effect of Frivolous Lawsuits on the Settlement of Litigation. 10, International Review of Law and Economics, 3-27. Kessler, D. (1996). Institutional Causes of Delay in the Settlement of Legal Disputes, 12, Journal of Law, Economics, and Organizations, 432-460. Kritzer, H.M. (2008) To Lawyer or Not to Lawyer: Is that the Question? 5, Journal of Empirical Legal Studies, 875-906. (2010). Examining the Real Demand for Legal Services. 37, Fordham Urban Law Journal, 255- 272. Landes, W.M. (1971). An Economic Analysis of the Court. 14, Journal of Law and Economics, 61-107. LEGAL SERVS. CORP. (2005). Documenting the Justice Gap in America: The Current Unmet Civil Legal Needs of Low-Income Americans 2005.www.lsc.gov/sites/default/files/LSC/images/justicegap.pdf (2009). Documenting the Justice Gap in America: The Current Unmet Civil Legal Needs of Low- Income Americans, 2009. www.lsc.gov/JusticeGap.pdf . Marshall, T.H. (1950). Citizenship and Social Class, and Other Essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Mattei, U. (2006). Access to Justice, Costs, and Legal Aid. XVII Congress of the International Academy of Comparative Law. Utrecht, The Netherlands Molot, J.T. (2010). Litigation Finance: A Market Solution to a Procedural Problem. 99, Georgetown Law Journal, (2010), 65-115. Mnookin, R.H. Why Negotiations fail: An Explorations of Barriers to the Resolution of Conflicts. 8, Ohaio state Journal on Dispute Resolution, 235-251. Nalebuff, B. (1987). Credible Pretrial Negotiation. 18, RAND Journal of Economics, 198-210. 29   North, D.C. (1989). Institutions and economic growth: an historical introduction.9, World Develop, 1319-1332. Pleasence, P., Balmer, N. J., and A. Buck, (2006). Causes of action: Civil law and social justice (2nd ed.). London: Legal Services Commission. (2008). The health cost of civil-law problems: Further evidence of links between civil-law problems and morbidity, and the consequential use of health services. 5, Journal of Empirical Legal Studies, 351-373. Pleasence, P., Balmer, N. J., Buck, A., O’Grady, A., and H. Genn. (2004). Civil law problems and morbidity. 58, Journal of Epidemiology and Community Health, 552-557. Pleasence, P., Balmer, N.J., Buck, A., Smith, M., and A. Patel. (2007). Mounting problems: Further evidence of the social, economic and health consequences of civil justice problems. In Pleasence, P., Buck, A., and N.J. Balmer, (Eds.), Transforming lives: Law and social process, 67-92. London: Legal Services Commission. P’ng, I.(1983). Strategic Behavior in Suit, Settlement, and Trial. 14, Bell Journal of Economics, 539- 550. Posner, R.A. (1973). An Economic Approach to Legal Procedure and Judicial Administration. 2, Journal of Legal Studies, 399-458. (1998). Creating a Legal Framework for Economic Development. 13, The World Bank Research Observer, 1-11. Polinsky, A.M. and D.L. Rubinfeld. (1993) Sanctioning Frivolous Suits: An Economic Analysis. 82 Georgia Law Journal, 397-436. (1988). The Deterrent Effect of Settlement and Trial. 8, International Review of Law and Economics, 109-116. Priest, G.L. and B. Klein. (1984). “The Selection of Disputes for Litigation. 13, Journal of Legal Studies, 1-56. Ramseyer, J.M. and E.B. Rasmusen. (2010). Comparative Litigation Rates. Harvard John M. Olin Discussion Paper Series, No. 681. Ringanum, J.F. and L.L. Wilde. (1986). Settlement, Litigation, and the Allocation of Litigation Costs. 17, RAND Journal of Economics, 557-566. Rhode, D.L. (2004). Access to justice. Oxford University Press, USA. Rodak, M. (2006). It’s About Time: A Systems Thinking Analysis of the Litigation Finance Industry and its Effect on Settlement. 155, University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 503-535. Rosemberg, D. and S. Shavell. (1985). A Model in which Suits are Brought for their Nuisance Value. 5, International Review of Law and Economics, 3-13. Rubinstein, A. (1982). Perfect Equilibrium in a Bargaining Model. 50, Econometrica, 97-110. Saraceno, M. (2008) Access to Justice and Litigation Trade-Off: A Theoretical Analysis. Paolo Baffi Centre Research Paper No. 2008-29; CLEA 2008 Meetings Paper. Shavell, S. (1982). The Social versus Private Incentive to Bring a Suit in Costly Legal System. 11, Journal of Legal Studies, 333-340. (1986). The Judgment Proof Problem. 6 International Review of Law and Economics, 45-58. (1995). Alternative Disputes Resolution: An Economic Analysis. 24, Journal of Legal Studies, 1- 28. (1997). The Fundamental Divergence between the Private and the Social Motive to Use the Legal System. 26, Journal of Legal Studies, 575-616. 30   (1999). The Level of Litigation: Private versus Social Optimality of Suit and of Settlement. 19, International Review of Law and Economics, 99-115. Schlesinger, R.B. (1988). Comparative law: cases, text, materials. Foundation Press. Schwartz, W.F. and Wickelgren, A.L. (2009). Advantage Defendant: Why Sinking Litigation Costs Makes Negative Expected Value Defenses, but not Negative Expected Value Suits, Credible. 38, Journal of Legal Studies, 235-253. Schweizer, U. (1989). Litigation and Settlement under Two Sided Incomplete Information. 56, Review of Economic Studies, 163-177. Silver, C. (2001). Does civil justice cost too much? 80, Texas Law Review, 2073-2114. Sommerlad, H (2004). Some Reflections on the Relationship between Citizenship, Access to Justice, and the Reform of Legal Aid. 31, Journal Law and Society, 345-368 Spier, K.E. (1992). The Dynamics of Pretrial Negotiation. 59, Review of Economic Studies, 93-108. (2007). “Litigation” in M. Polinsky and S. Shavell, (Eds.), Handbook of Law and Economics, Elsevier, 259-342. Stratton, M., and T. Anderson. (2008). Social, economic and health problems associated with a lack of access to the courts. Edmonton: Canadian Forum on Civil Justice. Summers, J. (1983). The Case of the Disappearing Defendant: An Economic Analysis. 132 University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 145-185 Trubek ,D.M., Sarat, A., Felstinert, W.L.F., Kritzert, H.M., and J.B. Grossmant. (1983). Costs of Ordinary Litigation. 31, UCLA Law Review, 72-127. UNDP. (2004). Access to Justice: Practice Note. United Nations Development Program Publications. (2010). Integrating Legal Empowerment of the Poor in UNDP’s work A Guidance Note. United Nations Development Program Publications. U.S. Deparment of Justice (2013). The Access to Justice Initiative of the U.S. Department of Justice. Access to Justice Accomplishments. Available at http://www.justice.gov/atj/accomplishments.pdf Varano, V. And A. De Luca. (2007). Access to Justice in Italy. 7, Global Jurist (Advances, art. 6). Wang, G.H., Kim, J.Y., and J.G. YI. (1994). Litigation and Pretrial Negotiation under Incomplete Information. 10, Journal of Law, Economics and Organization; 187-200. World Bank. (2006). World Development Report 2006: Equity and Development. New York: Oxford University Press Yildiz, M. (2003). Bargaining without a Common Prior - An Immediate Agreement Theorem. 71, Econometrica, 793-811. 31   Appendix A.1 Changes in the parameters can shift the analysis from case I to case II and vice versa. Note that the access-to justice threshold (hereafter, ) changes more sharply than the trial selection threshold (hereafter, ) for a given change in . For changes in , the does not change while moves. In addition, recalling that can be written as and as , changes in A move both the thresholds (both are decreasing in A). The following observations can be derived:  Significant increases in shift case I to case II. Significant decreases in shift case II to case I.  Significant decreases in shift case I to case II. Significant increases in shift case II to case I.  With respect to A, generally moves faster than . Actually, moves slower than iff , ( - setting overall costs equal to 1 this means ). This implies that significant decreases in A generally shift case I to case II.  Since case II corresponds to the parameter restriction , significant increases in A shift case II to case I ( ). Intuitively, it is possible understanding how changes in A shift the analysis from a case to the other moving on the Figure 2 from NE to SW for increases in A and from SW to NE for decreases in A. KJ c  (1 ) K K c c T c c        Kc c J  T  Kc K C A (1 ) K K c c c c      K K C C A C C      Kc Kc c c J  T  J  T  Kc c  iff 2( ) ( )²K K K T J c c c c c c A A               3 Kc c  / ( )K Kc c c c   J T A A        32   A.2 Partial derivatives of both absolute and standardized rates of access to justice, settlement and litigation are calculated with respect to the parameters of the model for cases I and II in Table A1 and A2, respectively. Table A1. Comparative statics: Case I Case I  Table A2. Comparative statics: Case II Case II        We focus on Table A1. Uncertain signs of case I are discussed below. First column. Signs of partial derivatives of the standardized rates of settlement and litigation with respect to K’s cost are uncertain . Focus on : denominator is positive and       0 2 1 3 0 1 3 1 1 <0 1 0 1 0 1 0 1 K K K K K K K K K K s c c c s c c c c c s ss c c c l c c c                                                       0 2 2 1 3 2 0 1 2 0 1 1 1 1 2 2 2 0 1 1 / / 0 K K K K K K K K K K K K K s J c c c c c c c c c c s J c c c c s J s J s J l J c c c c                                                  3 2 / 1 2 1 0 2 1 1 K K K K K l J c c c c c c c                              0 2 1 3 0 1 3 3 0 0 1 1 1 >0 1 0 1 1 0 1 1 0 1 / 0 / <0 / >0 / / 0 K K K K K K s c c c s c c c c c s ss c c c c c l c c c s J s J c c s J s J c c s J s J c c l J l J c c                                                                                            0 2 2 1 3 0 1 3 3 0 1 20 0 1 1 21 1 0 1 0 1 0 1 0 1 0 1 * * 0 * * 0 K K K K K K K K K K s c c c A A A c c c cs A A c c s s c c cs A A A A A c c c cl A A c c s J s J J s J A A A s J s J J s J A A A s J s J s J l A A A                                                                               1 2 0 / * * 0 J A l J l J J l J A A A                    1 0 / 1 > 0 2 / 1 < 0 2 0 K K K K K K l c c s J c l J c s c c                        0 0 0 / 0 s c l c s J c l J c                       2 0 1 0 1 0 2 / 1 0 2 K K K K K cs A A cl c A A s J c A A l J c A A                      / / 0 K K l J s J c c        / K l J c   33   the sign is driven by the numerator. . Recalling that and defining the absolute value of the elasticity of the “demand for justice” as , we can rewrite and then This means that the standardized rate of litigation decreases with an increase in claimant's litigation cost only if the demand for justice is sufficiently inelastic. For an elastic demand for justice, the standardized litigation rate always increases when claimants’ costs increase. Actually, increasing claimants’ costs reduce both the amount of disputes that go in trial and the amount of disputes that access justice. This combined action can increase the standardized (and observable) rate of litigation. The opposite reasoning is valid for the standardized rate of settlement. Third column. . Solving for , it becomes where . is represented on the -axes in the Figure A1 (green curve). Figure A1. Effects of changes in on the absolute rate of pooling settlement   0 for <1-3 / 0 for =1-3 0 for >1-3 K K K K c c l J c c c c c          1 KJ c  , K K J c K cJ c J       1 , ,1K KK J c J cc                    1 , 1 , 1 , 0 for < 1 2 <1 / 0 for 1 2 <1 0 for 1 2 <1 K K K J c J c K J c c c l J c c c c c                                         2 20 2 0 for < 1 0 for < 1 0 for < 1 K K K K K K K K K c c c c c s c c c c c A c c c c c                        c 1 2 0 1 2 1 2 0 for >{ ( ), ( )} 0 for { ( ), ( )} 0 for <{ ( ), ( )} K K K K K K c f c f c s c f c f c A c f c f c          2 2 1 2 1 1 ( ) (-2 (-4 1) - 2 1), ( ) - (2 (-4 1) 2 -1) 2 2 K K K K K K K K K K f c c c c f c c c c c c         1 2{ ( ), ( )} K Kc f c f c  Kc c A 34   The dashed dark line in the graph represents the elasticity of the demand for legal remedies that can be measured on the y-axis. An increase in the amount-at-stake decreases the rate of pooling settlement only when claimant’s costs are low enough (approximately smaller than 0.2)/the demand for legal remedies is sufficiently inelastic (approximately smaller than 0.3). When the demand is elastic (or with unitary elasticity), an increase in the amount-at-stake enlarges the rate of pooling settlement for every value of the defendant cost. Since , it is straightforward that the parameter restriction in terms of is more binding. To have a settlement rate decreasing in A, K’s cost/the elasticity of the demand for legal remedies has to be lower than that one to have a rate of pooling settlement decreasing in A. Therefore, an increase in the amount-at-stake reduces the rate of settlement only when claimant cost is very low/demand is strongly inelastic. Obviously, when . Finally, when the demand for legal remedies is elastic (or with unitary elasticity), an increase in the amount-at-stake enlarges the rate of settlement for every value of litigation costs. . Solving for , it becomes .   Recalling that , the parameter restriction can be written also in terms of elasticity of the demand for legal remedies: where . This means that the standardized rate of litigation increases with an increase in amount-at-stake only if the elasticity of the demand for justice is sufficiently low (not necessarily inelastic). For a sufficiently elastic demand for justice, the standardized litigation rate can be decreasing in A. The opposite reasoning is valid for the standardized rate of settlement.          3 3 3 0 for < 1 0 for < 1 0 for < 1 K K K K K K K K K c c c c c s c c c c c A c c c c c                        Kc 0 s A    0 0 s A                     0 for > 1 2 1 / 0 for = 1 2 1 0 < 1 2 1 K K K K K K K K K K K K c c c c c c l J c c c c c c A c c c c c c                        c                  1 1 1 0 for < 3 1 1- 3 1 / 0 for = 3 1 1- 3 1 0 for > 3 1 1- 3 1 K K K K K K K K K c c c c l J c c c c A c c c c                    1, ,1K KK J c J cc           , , , 0 for > 1 / 0 for 1 0 for 1 K K K J c J c J c l J A                  21 (c + 18c +9c +1+1) 1 2c +4        35   A.3. . Substituting by l and then by social cost of dispute resolution can be rewritten as for case I and for case II. Partial derivatives with respect to J are and for case I and II respectively. By replacing again in the expressions above, the conditions to have the social cost of dispute resolution decreasing in J are: and for case I and II respectively. The two conditions correspond to a unique condition equal for both cases: . A.4. Socially meritorious claims have been defined as those characterized by . It is socially efficient a complete subsidization when (6.1). For case II which is always larger than . Therefore it is always efficient subsidizing all socially meritorious claims falling in case II. For case I, is larger than for corresponding to (see A.1.). Therefore, for socially meritorious claims with elasticity of the demand for legal remedies smaller than  condition (6.1) is always verified. For claims falling in case I and characterized by elasticity equal to /larger than ,  condition (6.1) has to be satisfied in order to have efficient subsidization.  1 Jl     1Kc J     21 2 12 JJ c       2 1 1 2 JJ        32 0J c J            0J J        1 KJ c    31 Kc c J           1 Kc J        0 iff K l J c         Kl c     l J   1 K K l c c      1 2 1 Kl J c    3 1K Kl c c c           2 1 1 11 2 K K l J c c c       <1-3 Kc c  ,